Skip to main content

Full text of "Strauss as a philosophical thinker : a review of his book, "The old faith and the new faith", and a confutation of its materialistic views"

See other formats


LIBRARY  OF  COxNGRESS.  I 


0  . ^ I 

f UNITED  STATES  OF  AMERICA    f 


-  ^:^- 


STRAUSS  AS  A  PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 


A  REVIEW 


OF  HIS  BOOK, 


"  THE  OLD  FAITH  AND  THE  NEW  FAITH," 


AND 


A  CONFUTATION  OF  ITS  MATERIALISTIC  VIEWS. 


BY 


HEKMAK:]Sr  TJLEICI. 


TRANSLATED,  WITH  AN  INTRODUCTION, 

BY 

CHAELES  P.  KEAUTH,  D.D., 

VICE-PROVOST  OF  THE  UNIVERSITY  OF  PENNSYLVANIA. 


PHILADELPHIA:     N^:^  t--r«#1  ^ 
SMITH,   ENGLISH   &  COT,       "^ 

710  ARCH  STREET. 

EDIKBUKGH:  T.  &  T.  CLARK. 

1874. 


Entered  according  to  Act  of  Congress,  in  the  year  1874, 

By  smith,  ENGLISH  &  CO., 

In  the  Office  of  the  Librarian  of  Congress,  at  Washington,  D.  C. 


PHILADELPHIA ! 
SHERMAN  &  CO.,  PRINTERS. 


CONTENTS. 


INTRODUCTION: 

The  Materialism  of  our  Day, 

Aim  of  the  Present  Discussion, 

Importance  of  the  Question,  . 

The  Problem  of  the  Hour, 

The  Materialistic  Physicists,  . 

Materialism  a  Power  in  our  Day, 

Necessity  of  Discussing  Materialism, 

Kecent  Discussions — Appearance  of  Strauss's  Book 

Strauss's  Keviewers, 

Points  of  Interest  in  the  Reviews  of  Strauss, 
Strauss's  Inconsistency  with  his  Earlier  Position 

The  Great  Physicists, 

Mischievous  Tendencies  of  Strauss's  Book,    . 
The  Political  Elements  in  Strauss, 
The  Reactionary  Tendency  of  Strauss's  Book, 
Ulrici'S  Review  of  Strauss,     .... 

ULRICrS  REVIEW  OF  STRAUSS: 

I.  Strauss  considered  as  a  Philosophical  Thinker, 
II.  What  Strauss  proposes  in  *'  The  New  Faith 
and  the   Old  Faith:"    his  real   aim   the 
Destruction  of  the  Old  Faith,    . 
III.  ''Are  we  still  Christians?". 
lY.  ''Have  we  Religion  still?"  . 
Y.  Strauss's  Theory  of  the  Rise  of  Religion,    . 
YI.  Strauss's  Repudiation  of  the  Argument  for 
the  Existence  of  God,        .... 


PAGE 

9 
13 
14 
21 
22 
25 
27 
31 
35 
39 
49 
51 
58 
63 
65 
67 

73 


75 
78 
79 
84 

86 


Vlll  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

YII.  Immortality  of  the  Soul,     ....  91 

VIII.  The  Essential  Nature  of  Keligion,       .         .  92 
IX.  The  Permanent  in  Keligion — Man  and  the 

Universe, 95 

X.  The  New  Faith, 98 

XI.  The  Discovery, 100 

XII.  The  Good  and  the  Bad,         .         .         .         .104 
XIII.  Strauss  in  Conflict  with  consistent  Materi- 
alism ;  Pessimism  ;   Schopenhauer ;   Yon 

Hartmann, 106 

Xiy.  ^'  What  is  our  Apprehension  of  the   Uni- 
verse?''       108 

XY.  The  Cosmogony  of  Kant  and  La  Place,       .  113 
XYI.  Origin    of    Life    upon     Earth — Generatio 

-^quivoca — Organic  and  Inorganic,          .  115 

XYII.  Origin  of  Species — The  Darwinian  Theory,  120 
XYIII.  The  Ape  and  Man — Man  and  the  Animals, 

their  Affinities  and  Distinctions,       .         .  125 
XIX.  The  Soul,       .         .         .         .         .         .         .128 

XX.  Strauss's  Appeal  to  Du  Bois-Reymond,         .  133 
XXI.  The  Notion  of  Design  in  the  Light  of  Natural 

Science — Philosophy  of  the  Unconscious,  137 
XXII.  The  setting  aside  of  the  Doctrine  of  Einal 

Causes  in  Nature  by  Darwin,    .         .         .  139 

XXIII.  <^  How  shall  we  Order  our  Life  V        .         .  144 

XXIY.  The  Primary  Principle  of  Morality,    .         .  146 
XXY.  Strauss's  attempt  to  show  that  he  does  not  hold 

that  the  Universe  is  a  thing  of  Chance,  .  152 

XXYI.  Nature  coming  to  Self-recognition,      .         .  155 

XXYII.  Strauss's  direct  Contradiction  of  himself,    .  158 
XXYIII.  Strauss's  Ideal  Strivings — His  Recognition 

of  Mystery, 160 

XXIX.  Conclusion— The  New  Philosophy,      .        .  162 


INTEODUCTION. 


THE  MATERIALISM  OF  OUR  DAY. 

To  any  reader  who  knows  the  vast  range  of 
topics  involved  in  a  complete  discussion  of 
Materialism,  the  very  dimensions  of  the  volume 
he  holds  in  his  hand  would  show  that  it  pro- 
poses to  touch  upon  no  more  than  a  part  of  a 
part  of  that  vast  theme.  For  the  questions  of 
Materialism  cover  the  physical,  intellectual  and 
moral  universe.  There  is  nothing  deep  or  high 
in  man's  life,  or  thinking,  in  his  present  or  his 
future,  which  they  do  not  in  some  measure 
condition.  Materialism  calls  for  an  obliteration 
of  what  is  noblest  in  the  past,  the  abandonment 
of  our  richest  heritages,  and  a  total  reconstruc- 
tion of  all  the  present,  an  abrupt  change  in  all 
that  tended  to  a  future  with  roots  deepset  in 
the  past.  If  Materialism  be  successful  in  estab- 
lishing its  claim,  it  will  involve  the  greatest 
revolution  which  has  ever  taken  place  in  the 


10  INTRODUCTION. 

world.  To  make  this  volume  a  complete  sum- 
mary, not  to  sa}^  a  survey  of  all  the  facts  and 
principles  which  are  covered  by  the  assertion 
and  exposure  of  such  a  system  as  Materialism, 
would  involve  the  compression  of  a  world  to 
the  dimensions  of  a  pea.  All  sciences  have 
been  made  tributary  to  the  false  assumptions  of 
the  Materialism  of  our  day,  and  all  the  sciences 
would  have  to  be  laid  under  contribution  to  fur- 
nish the  refutation  of  it.  Here,  as  everywhere 
the  great  corrective  of  abuse  is  the  restoration 
of  the  right  use.  The  fact  that  the  abuse  of 
science  has  been  made  to  sustain  Materialism  is 
itself  the  best  evidence  that  the  right  use  of 
science  will  most  completely  overthrow  Mate- 
rialism. If  so  much  science  promotes  Materi- 
alism, it  is  proof  not  that  we  need  less  science, 
but  that  we  need  more.  So  much  more  will 
undo  the  mischief  which  so  much  has  done. 
Only  let  the  science  be  real  science,  and  there 
cannot  be  too  much  of  it.  To  appeal  from 
science  in  its  legitimate  sphere,  to  authority,  in 
behalf  of  religion,  is  not  to  secure  religion  but 
to  betray  it.  Science  and  Religion  are  occupied 
with  two  books,  but  both  books  are  from  one 
hand;  in  their  true  workings  they  are  engaged 
in  two  parts  of  one  great  aim.  Science  moves 
ever  toward  the  proof  how  supernatural  is  the 


THE   MATERIALISM   OF   OUR   DAY.  11 

natural ;  Religion  moves  toward  the  proof  how 
natural  is  the  supernatural.  For  nature  in  the 
narrower  sense,  is  in  her  spring,  Supernatural. 
To  this  point  all  natural  science  constantlj^  ad- 
vances. The  more  problems  natural  science 
settles  the  more  it  raises ;  the  more  it  diminishes 
the  sphere  in  which  the  speculation  of  the  past 
found  its  range,  the  more  does  it  enlarge  the 
sphere  of  the  future  speculation.  Ours  is  at 
once  the  age  of  the  suprernest  affluence  in  ques- 
tions solved,  and  of  the  most  pressing  poverty 
in  questions  opened  and  unanswered.  A  ques- 
tion settled  is  a  question  planted,  and  green, 
young  questions  spring  all  around  it.  The  more 
we  know  of  l^ature,  the  more  cogent  becomes 
the  necessity  of  the  Supernatural.  On  the 
other  hand,  the  Supernatural  is  within  Nature, 
in  Nature's  broader  sense.  In  this  sense  Nature 
is  identical  with  the  real.  Everything  is  Nature 
that  is  not  non-nature;  everything  is  natural 
that  is  not  unnatural.  The  Supernatural  is  not 
to  be  construed  as  the  contranatural,  but  as  the 
natural  itself  in  its  supremest  sphere,  and  God 
and  His  directest  works  are  supernatural  because 
they  are  by  pre-eminence  natural.  In  this  sense 
Nature  is  not  a  conception  embraced  in  the  con- 
ception of  God,  but  as  all-embracing,  most  of 
all  embraces  God  as  the  Supreme  Nature,  whose 


12  INTRODUCTION. 

most  supernatural  works,  are,  as  such,  most 
natural.  The  sciences  which  represent  nature, 
and  the  faith  to  which  are  committed  the  oracles 
of  the  Supernatural,  must  in  proportion  as  they 
prove  true  to  themselves,  prove  true  to  each 
other.  Whatever  may  be  the  apparent  difier- 
ence  of  their  origin,  though  the  one  seem  to 
spring  out  of  the  earth,  the  other  to  look  down 
from  heaven,  knowledge  and  faith  shall  at  last 
meet  together  and  kiss  each  other.  It  is  a 
common  canon  of  science  and  religion  to  "judge 
nothing  before  the  time,"  and  yet  it  is  the  neg- 
lect of  this  canon  on  both  sides  which  has 
been  the  occasion  of  their  most  serious  misun- 
derstandings and  of  their  sharpest  collisions. 
Some  who  have  professed  to  represent  science, 
have  been  too  ready  with  their  theories,  and 
some  who  have  claimed  to  be  special  defenders 
of  the  faith  have  been  too  absolute  in  their  in- 
terpretations, and  it  is  precisely  between  pro- 
visional dogmatical  theories,  and  provisional 
dogmatic  interpretations,  the  severest  conflict 
has  taken  place.  It  has  been  a  battle  of  guesses. 
The  warfare  will  ultimately  be  laid  by  the  over- 
throw of  the  hasty  theory,  or  of  the  hasty  in- 
terpretation, or  of  both. 


AIM   OF   THE   PEESENT   DISCUSSION.  13 


AIM  OF  THE  PRESENT  DISCUSSION. 

Fully  to  discuss  Materialism,  which  assumes 
to  be  the  philosophy  of  all  knowledge,  would 
involve  in  the  nature  of  the  case  a  presentation 
of  an  immense  body  of  facts,  drawn  from  the 
intellectual  and  moral  sciences.  Simply  to 
state  the  misstatements  of  Materialism  without 
correcting  them,  or  to  give  its  arguments  with- 
out answering  them,  would  demand  a  series  of 
elaborate  and  ponderous  volumes.  And  yet 
this  little  volume,  meant  for  the  fireside  and 
the  pocket,  is  large  enough  and  rich  enough,  to 
give  both  sides  of  this  great  question,  in  the 
words  of  very  able  representatives  of  both.  It 
is  sufficiently  comprehensive  at  least  to  help  the 
reader  to  test  what  Materialism  is  made  of,  and 
to  settle  the  question  whether  we  are  willing  to 
have  the  edifice  of  our  convictions  built  of  it. 
In  our  schoolday  Greek  reading,  under  the 
painful  embarrassment  with  which  a  grammar 
and  dictionary  invest  the  ordinarily  spontaneous 
process  of  laughing,  we  were  taught  to  laugh  at 
the  Scholastikos,  the  Greek  Irishman,  who  hav- 
ing a  house  to  sell,  carried  around  a  brick  as  a 
specimen  of  it.  But  the  Scholastikos,  as  the 
Irishman  not  unfrequently  is,  was  perhaps  wiser 


14  INTRODUCTION. 

than  some  who  laughed  at  him.  The  brick 
settled  at  least  one  question,  and  in  settling  that, 
settled  to  many  a  man  all  the  other  questions. 
To  the  man  who  wanted  a  house  of  marble,  the 
brick  settled  it,  that  the  house  of  whose  material 
if  was  a  specimen  was  not  the  house  he  wanted. 
This  volume  carries  with  it,  both  in  the  state- 
ments of  Strauss,  which  are  given  in  his  own 
words,  and  in  the  replies  of  Ulrici,  enough 
evidence  to  decide  what  Materialism  is.  It 
shows  in  that  very  world  of  scientific  fact  and 
of  speculative  thought  in  which  Materialism  is 
most  boastful  and  arrogant,  how  little  it  has  to 
tempt  the  thoughtful  man  to  forego  the  use  of 
logical  reason,  how  little  to  justify  the  good 
man  in  doing  violence  to  his  moral  sense.  It 
shows  that  sunbaked  mud  bricks,  all  the  weaker 
for  the  shining  particles  glittering  in  them,  com- 
pose the  building  with  which  Materialism  pro- 
poses to  replace  the  edifice  of  human  convictions 
and  faiths,  which  have  stood  unmoved  through 
the  storms  of  age. 


IMPORTANCE  OF  THE  QUESTION. 

It  is  impossible  for  the  thinkers  of  our  day  to 
look  with  indifl:erence  on  its  materialistic  ten- 
dencies.   If  views  of  this  class  possess,  in  them- 


IMPORTANCE   OF   THE   QUESTION.  15 

selves,  little  philosophical  importance,  they  yet 
have  a  claim  on  our  attention,  not  only  because 
of  the  great  mischief  they  may  produce,  but 
also  because  they  are  bearing  a  part  in  widen- 
ing and  intensifying  that  general  interest  in 
the  natural  sciences,  of  which  they  are  in  part 
the  effect,  in  part  the  cause.  All  the  intensest 
passions  of  our  human  life  gather  about  some 
sort  of  battle.  The  unfought  is  unfelt.  The 
materialistic  struggle  more  than  anj'thing  else 
vitalizes  the  natural  sciences — for  thinking  is, 
after  all,  the  supremest  pleasure  of  thinking 
man.  The  intellectual  beats  the  material  in  all 
long  races.  In  the  struggle  which  Materialism 
has  produced,  germs  have  been  scattered,  and 
are  already  springing,  which  sooner  or  later  will 
modify  in  important  respects  the  philosophy  of 
the  future.  The  inflaence  of  the  natural  sci- 
ences in  the  sphere  of  philosophy  is  more 
marked  in  our  own  day  than  at  any  period 
since  Aristotle,  Master  of  Physics  and  Master 
of  Metaphj^sics,  laid  in  the  one  the  basis  of  the 
other.  Our  age  pays,  not  for  the  first  time,  the 
greatest  of  tributes  received  by  that  wonderful 
man — the  tribute  of  denouncing  him  and  his 
method,  meaning  neither  the  real  Aristotle,  nor 
the  real  Aristotelian  method,  and  then  following 


16  INTRODUCTION. 

more  closely  than  before  in  the  real  walk  of  the 
great  Peripatetic.     Ours  is  an  Aristotelian  age. 

In  one  respect,  indeed,  these  last  days  of 
philosophy  tend  in  a  dangerous  respect  to  be 
like  its  very  first — to  make  Physics  everything 
and  Metaphysics  nothing.  But  the  difierence 
is  nevertheless  marked,  between  the  earliest 
and  latest  eras.  Physical  observation,  in  our 
day,  has  developed  into  science ;  all  the  depart- 
ments of  the  natural  sciences  have  been  im- 
mensely enriched,  and  some  of  the  most  bril- 
liant discoveries  of  all  time  have  been  made. 

This  has  naturally  led  to  a  predominance  of 
that  class  of  interests  over  every  other.  Ours 
is  the  era  of  the  physical  sciences,  and  of  their 
tributaries  and  applications.  These  have  thrown 
into  the  shade  all  the  other  departments  of 
human  thought.  Not  even  civil  and  political 
issues  have  excited  the  interest  in  the  intel- 
lectual world  which  is  excited  by  the  great 
physicists.  Our  poets,  statesmen  and  soldiers 
have  not  given  to  us  a  household  name  more 
frequently  on  our  lips  than  that  of  Agassiz.  l^o 
Englishmen  are  spoken  of  more  than  Darwin 
and  Tyndall  ;  and  Humboldt,  Lotze,  Helm- 
HOLTZ,  and  a  host  of  others,  shine  with  peculiar 
splendor  in  the  great  galaxy  of  the  Germany 
of  our  age. 


IMPOETANCE   OF   THE   QUESTION.  17 

It  is,  however,  especially  the  philosophical  sci- 
ences which  have  been  injured  by  the  predomi- 
nance of  physical  studies,  when  these  studies 
have  assumed  the  unnatural  position,  not  of  pre- 
supposition to  the  metaphysical,  a  place  which  is 
rightly  their  due,  but  of  antagonism  to  it. 
Physical  science  seems,  indeed,  to  furnish  a 
strong  contrast  to  Metaphysics ;  the  one  seems 
so  fruitful  a  field,  the  other  so  barren  an  arena; 
the  one  claims  the  power  of  enforcing  convic- 
tion of  its  facts  on  every  intelligent  mind,  the 
other  is  apparently  incapable  of  healing  the 
divisions  it  originates.  The  physical  sciences 
seem  so  useful  in  everyday  life,  going  down  to 
the  heart  of  the  world  to  warm  and  enrich  us, 
and  challenging  clouds  and  stars  to  help  the 
husbandman  and  the  sailor.  In  contrast  with 
them  the  metaphysical  sciences  seem  so  atten- 
uated, so  utterly  vague !  Mills  do  not  grind, 
nor  engines  labor  at  their  command.  They  do 
not  put  fruits  upon  our  tables,  nor  fill  our  fields 
with  springing  grass  for  our  herds.  This  con- 
trast becomes  the  more  specious  and  more  un- 
favorable to  Metaphysics,  because  few  compar- 
atively have  a  clear  conception  of  the  relation 
of  the  physical  and  the  intellectual  sciences. 
Where  a  comparison  is  made,  it  is  often  made 
between  the  highest  forms  of  the  physical  sci- 


18  INTRODUCTION. 

ences,  and  the  weakest  and  most  extravagant 
forms  of  metaphysical  speculation.  We  are 
asked  to  look  upon  the  picture  of  some  Hype- 
rion of  the  one,  by  the  side  of  some  Satyr  of  the 
other.  Those  who  know  the  facts,  know  that  the 
philosophical  spirit  is  the  spirit  which  vitalizes 
all  the  material  with  the  mental,  and  connects  all 
phenomena  with  conceptions  of  the  essence  they 
represent,  all  facts  with  truth,  all  effects  with 
causes,  all  that  is  individual  with  the  coherence 
of  relations,  all  premises  with  inferences,  all  the 
transient  with  the  ultimate.  They  know  that 
it  is  the  spirit  which  lays  the  whole  realm  of 
nature  under  tribute,  and  that  without  this 
spirit,  and  the  results  of  its  life  in  men,  and  its 
labor  for  men,  we  should  have  no  natural 
sciences.  It  is  imminent  in  them  even  w^hen 
they  know  it  not;  its  death  would  be  their 
death.  It  is  the  life-unit  of  the  coral-bed 
of  the  accretions  of  physics.  The  physical 
sciences  are  but  one  efflorescence,  among  the 
innumerable  forms  in  which  the  philosophical 
spirit  reveals  itself.  All  the  physical  sciences, 
as  sciences,  rest  upon  metaphysical  data,  and 
develop  themselves  toward  metaphysical  se- 
quences. The  intensest  interest  of  cultivated 
minds,  in  the  very  sphere  of  what  seems  most 
like   unrelievable    physics,    turns    toward   the 


IMPORTANCE   OF  THE   QUESTION.  19 

theory,  the  hypothesis,  the  speculation  it  in- 
volves. Without  the  metaphysical  spirit,  the 
chemist  sinks  to  the  condition  of  the  other  com- 
pound substances  of  his  laboratory;  the  astron- 
omer is  but  a  big  child  playing  with  a  big 
Orrery;  the  geologist  possesses  the  penetration 
of  an  artesian  auger — no  more.  Such  men  are 
but  the  tools  of  science,  not  its  masters.  The 
grand  interest  which  attaches  to  modern  science, 
is  at  its  root  an  interest  in  the  philosophy  it 
involves.  An  author  like  Lewes  writes  a  very 
charming  book,  the  theory  of  whose  theory  is, 
that  the  metaphysical  sciences  are  of  no  value, 
the  theory  of  whose  existence  as  an  elaborate 
and  favorite  work  of  its  author  and  of  the  pub- 
lic is,  that  the  history  of  these  valueless  things 
has  an  enchantment  of  some  supreme  order  for 
himself  and  them.  But  after  Lewes  has  warned 
men  from  metaphysics,  by  the  very  inconsistent 
process  of  fascinating  them  with  its  history,  he 
discovers  that,  after  all,  Comte  and  the  Positivist 
school  to  the  contrary  notwithstanding,  man 
cannot  live  by  bread  alone.  He  has  found  that 
his  own  intellectual  life  could  not  endure  the 
self-imposed  starvation  produced  by  abstinence 
from  its  true  food.  As  the  result  of  his  larger 
experience,  he  makes  a  "  change  of  front,"  and 
tries  to  cover  his  movement  by  masking  it  with 


20  INTRODUCTION. 

the  name  of  "  Metempyrics.'^  He  has  shown 
that  even  a  very  poor  system  of  metaphysics  is 
better  than  none,  for  Lewes's  system  is  nothing 
more  than  the  hoary,  but  not  venerable,  old 
Sensualism,  with  his  hair  dyed,  and  pantaloons 
substituted  for  knee-breeches. 

Not  only  cannot  the  twin  sciences  be  sundered, 
but  they  cannot  bear  healthfully  a  restriction  of 
their  vital  intercommunication.  To  bind  the 
ligament  produces  a  fainting,  which  would  be 
followed  by  death.  It  is  therefore  a  shallow  and 
ignorant  impression,  though  sometimes  cher- 
ished by  men  who  ought  to  be  ashamed  to  har- 
bor it,  that  Philosophy  in  our  day  has  played 
out  its  part,  and  that  the  best  thing  would  be  to 
hasten  its  absorption  into  physics  and  physiol- 
ogy. In  this  extravagant  feeling  and  the  sources 
of  it,  Materialism  has  found  its  account.  The 
greatest  representatives  of  Materialism  have 
been,  for  the  most  part,  physiologists  and  physi- 
cians, and  from  the  same  professional  ranks  have 
come  some  of  its  most  thorough  and  vigorous 
assailants,  for  by  a  necessary  law  we  look  for 
the  wildest  errors,  the  most  progressive  truths, 
the  soberest  conservatism  in  the  same  general 
class  of  observers.  Theological  heresies  origi- 
nate with  theologians,  and  so  do  the  refutations 
of  heresies.     The  clergy  corrupt  the  Church — 


THE  PROBLEM  OF  THE  HOUR.       21 

they  also  reform  it;  and  because  physicians  and 
physicists  have  done  so  much  in  producing  Ma- 
terialism, we  look  to  physicians  and  physicists 
to  do  a  great  work  in  counteracting  and  heal- 
ing it. 


THE  PROBLEM  OF  THE  HOUR. 

It  is  admitted  that  in  scientific  thinking  the 
recent  Materialism  has  scarcely  brought  in  a 
single  new  idea.  It  has  added  nothing  appre- 
ciable to  La  Mettrie,  Diderot,  and  Von  Hol- 
BACH.  In  fact,  some  of  the  theories  passing  as 
novelties  in  our  own  day,  belong  to  a  very  re- 
mote antiquity.  But  this  by  no  means  proves 
that  the  Materialism  of  the  hour  has  no  signifi- 
cance in  Philosophy.  It  sustains  the  old  theo- 
ries by  a  vast  accumulation  of  new  facts.  The 
problem  of  the  hour  on  one  side  is  that  Philos- 
ophy shall  demonstrate  its  present  harmony 
with  the  facts  established  by  Physics,  or  failing 
to  do  this,  shall  adjust  itself  to  them.  On  the 
other  side,  it  is  incumbent  on  the  physical  sci- 
ences to  use  their  treasures  and  their  advanced 
condition  to  aid  in  producing  a  philosophical 
system,  in  which  the  external  world  shall  har- 
monize with  the  great  metaphysical  facts,  for 
such  facts  there  are,  more  certain  than  those  of 


22  INTRODUCTION. 

physics:  on  their  certainty,  indeed,  all  physical 
certainty  depends.  No  part  of  the  body  of 
knowledge  can  say  to  another  part,  "  I  have  no 
need  of  thee !" 

The  duty  of  aid  and  the  necessity  of  harmony 
between  these  two  great  departments  of  knowl- 
edge has  been  profoundly  felt  by  the  ablest  in- 
vestigators of  all  time,  and  with  increasing  force 
to  the  present  hour,  in  which  the  conviction  cul- 
minates. 'No  man  can  take  the  highest  rank  as 
a  physicist  or  metaphysician,  who  is  not  both 
physicist  and  metaphysician.  He  is  not  of  ne- 
cessity equally  both,  but  in  whichever  depart- 
ment he  may  be  by  pre-eminence,  his  greatness 
involves  a  thorough  acquaintance  with  at  least 
the  results  of  the  other.  In  the  past,  among  the 
names  that  have  intertwined  both  glories  in  one 
wreath,  are  the  nam  es  of  Aristotle,  Des  Cartes, 
Pascal,  Leibnitz,  Kant,  Schelling,  Schaller, 
and  Hegel.  Among  the  living  may  be  men- 
tioned men  like  Helmholtz,  Lotze,  Fichte,  and 
Ulrici. 

the  materialistic  physicists. 

The  very  roll-call  of  great  names  in  the  battle 
against  Materialism  shows  how  great  is  that 
battle,  and  how  materialistic  is  our  asce.  We 
see,  indeed,  very  often  assertions  to  the  con- 


THE   MATERIALISTIC   PHYSICISTS.  23 

trary.  Sometimes  they  are  made  in  pure  igno- 
rance by  good  people,  whose  happy  little  world 
is  their  fireside.  Sometimes  they  are  made  in 
the  blind  polemical  spirit  which  assumes  that 
denial  is  disproof.  Nevertheless  it  is  true,  this 
is  a  materialistic  age.  The  progress  of  physical 
science,  the  splendor  of  recent  discovery,  the 
wonderful  confirmation  of  the  acutest  conjec- 
tures of  the  past,  the  lustre  of  the  names  asso- 
ciated with  these  movements,  have  seemed  to 
justify  the  physicists  of  our  day  in  their  exuber- 
ant triumph  in  the  present  achievements  in  the 
world  of  matter,  and  in  their  boundless  assurance 
in  regard  to  the  future.  No  men  have  such  pro- 
phetic souls  as  sanguine  physicists.  These  theo- 
rists sometimes  ask  no  more  than  a  boundless 
past  to  justify  their  theories,  or  not  unfrequently 
appeal,  as  if  the  gaze  of  the  seer  w^ere  granted 
them,  to  that  happier  future  which  is  to  furnish 
the  missing  links  in  the  chain  of  demonstration. 
The  sole  reason  that  they  cannot  make  out  the 
theory  of  the  present  is,  either  that  they  cannot 
see  quite  far  enough  back  into  the  past,  or  can- 
not see  quite  far  enough  into  the  future,  except 
in  the  power  of  that  theoretic  faith  which,  dis- 
daining such  easy  things  as  removing  mountains, 
creates  or  uncreates  universes  at  pleasure,  and 
plays  with  nebulae  as  boys  play  with  marbles. 


24  INTRODUCTION. 

They  utterly  shame  the  believers  in  Revelation 
by  the  way  in  which  they  make  faith  the  sub- 
stance of  things  hoped  for,  and  the  evidence  of 
things  not  seen. 

Darwinism  has  simply  to  get  far  enough  back 
to  reach  the  ape  of  the  past,  to  see  him  in  the 
way  of  evolution  to  the  man  of  the  present,  or 
to  plunge  deeply  enough  into  the  ages  to  come 
to  see  some  man  of  the  future  evolved  from  an 
ape  of  the  present — for  we  are  primal  to  the  fu- 
ture as  the  past  is  primal  to  us — and  then  the 
theory  has  a  fact  which  fairly  supports  it — a 
something  it  does  not  possess  to  this  hour. 
And  as  Darwinism  needs  but  one  of  these  two 
little  things  to  make  it  an  established  theory, 
and  as  it  has  the  boundless  past  to  furnish  one, 
the  endless  future  to  furnish  the  other — why, 
in  a  matter  which  may  require  hunting  to  all 
eternity,  should  we  attempt  to  hurry  these 
trusting  adherents,  in  the  production  of  this 
fact?  If  they  wish  to  meet  the  debts  of  sci- 
ence by  renewing  its  notes,  they  have  many 
mercantile  precedents  for  the  method,  which 
postpones  the  crash,  even  when  it  does  not  pre- 
vent it.  If  the  enthusiast  in  the  physical  the- 
ories of  the  hour  is  willing  to  promise  the  bear- 
skin before  he  has  caught  the  bear,  is  not  that 
a  reason,  in  the  judgment  of  charity,  why  we 


MATERIALISM   A   POWER  IN   OUR   DAY.        25 

should  pardon  him  if,  in  fact,  he  sometimes 
mistakes  the  promise  of  the  skin  for  the  actual 
possession  of  the  bear,  and  that  instead  of  con- 
sidering the  theory  as  a  thing  to  be  proven,  he 
lays  it  down  as  a  first  principle  by  which  every- 
thing known  is  to  be  explained,  and  in  virtue 
of  which  everything  desired  is  to  be  assumed  ? 


MATERIALISM  A  POWER  IK  OUR  DAY. 

The  lowest  and  the  most  practical  of  the 
characteristics  of  our  day  unite  with  some  of  its 
most  brilliant  and  extravagant,  to  give  to  Ma- 
terialism a  special  potency.  In  no  land  is  the 
temptation,  in  some  of  its  forms,  greater  than 
in  our  own,  where  material  nature  in  her  un- 
subdued majesty  challenges  man  to  conflict,  or, 
in  her  fresh  charms  and  munificent  life,  lures 
him  to  devotion.  Materialism  is  popularized  in 
our  day.  The  magazines  and  papers  are  full  of 
it.  It  creeps  in  everywhere,  in  the  text-books, 
in  school-books,  in  books  for  children,  and  in 
popular  lectures.  Materialism  has  entered  into 
the  great  institutions  of  Germany,  England,  and 
America.  Our  old  seats  of  orthodoxy  have 
been  invaded  by  it.  IJew  England,  the  storm- 
gauge  of  the  rising  thought  of  our  land,  begins 
to  quiver  on  the  edge  of  the  coming  hurricane. 


26  INTRODUCTION. 

The  Materialism  of  our  day  is  very  versatile. 
It  takes  many  shapes,  often  avoids  a  sharp  con- 
flict, assumes  the  raiment  of  light,  knows  how 
to  play  well  the  parts  of  free  thought,  truth, 
and  beneficence.  All  the  more  securely  does  it 
pass  in  everywhere,  so  that  we  have  Material- 
ism intellectual,  domestic,  civil,  philanthropic, 
and  religious.  Strangest  of  all,  in  a  philosoph- 
ical point  of  view,  we  have  systems,  like  the 
system  of  Schopenhauer,  for  example,  which, 
under  the  form  of  the  supremest  Idealism,  have 
the  practical  power  of  the  lowest  Materialism. 
Beginning  in  the  sublimation  of  the  spirit,  they 
end  by  wallowing  in  the  filthiest  sty  of  the  flesh. 

Much  of  the  Materialism  of  our  day  is  servile 
and  dogmatic,  implicit  in  credulity,  and  insolent 
in  assertion.  Professing  to  be  independent  of 
names,  and  calling  men  to  rally  about  the  stand- 
ard of  absolute  freedom  from  all  authority,  it 
parades  names  where  it  has  names  to  parade, 
and  vilifies  the  fair  fame  of  those  whom  it  can- 
not force  into  acquiescence  or  silence.  Claim- 
ing to  be  free  from  partisanship,  it  is  full  of 
coarse  intolerance.  It  is  an  inquisition,  with 
such  tortures  as  the  spirit  of  our  age  still  leaves 
possible.  The  rabies  theologorum  of  which  it 
loves  to  talk,  pales  before  the  rabies  physicorum 
of  this  class,  sometimes  as  directed  against  each 


NECESSITY   OF   DISCUSSING   MATERIALISM.       27 

other,  yet  more  as  directed  against  the  men  of 
science  or  of  the  church,  who  resist  tlieir 
tlieories.  ''  If,"  says  Erdmann,  '*  we  are  to 
"suppose  that  natural  philosophy  teaches  us  to 
"  be  dogmatic  on  topics  about  which  we  under- 
"  stand  nothing,  then  has  natural  philosopliy 
"  never  found  such  zealous  adepts  as  are  found 
"  amons:  those  who  claim  to  be  exact  investio-a- 
"tors.  Anybody  in  our  day  who  knows  how 
"  to  handle  a  microscope,  imagines  that  without 
"anything  further,  he  can  venture  to  be  oracu- 
"lar  on  cause,  condition,  force,  matter,  logical 
"  law,  and  truth." 


NECESSITY   OF  DISCUSSING  MATERIALISM. 

These  are  a  few  of  the  indisputable  facts 
w^hich  show  that  by  pre-eminence  Materialism 
is  at  once  the  greatest,  both  of  the  speculative 
and  practical  questions  of  the  hour.  Yet  there 
are  good  and  intelligent  people  who  object  even 
to  an  exposure  of  Materialism  which  ma^'  inci- 
dentally bring  it  to  the  notice  of  some,  who 
they  imagine,  would  apart  from  such  an  ex- 
posure, have  remained  in  ignorance  or  indiffer- 
ence as  to  the  whole  subject.  They  think  that 
these  views,  pernicious  as  they  justly  regard 
them,  and  indeed,  because  they  do  so  regard 


28  INTRODUCTION. 

them,  should  be  kept  completely  out  of  sight 
wherever  it  is  possible.  It  is  quite  possible  that 
some  may  think  that  a  knowledge  of  Ulrici's 
refutation  is  too  dearly  purchased  by  the  knowl- 
edge of  Strauss's  errors  which  goes  with  it. 

To  such  objections  we  answer,  First :  Ignor- 
ance is  neither  innocence  nor  safet3\  Knowl- 
edge, indeed,  like  all  possessions,  is  capable  of 
abuse.  There  is  danger  in  whatever  we  do, 
and  wherever  there  is  danger  in  doing,  there 
may  be  danger  in  leaving  undone.  There  is 
danger  of  accident  in  exercise,  there  is  the 
greater  danger  of  loss  of  health  in  not  exercis- 
ing; there  is  the  danger  of  choking,  or  of  sur- 
feiting in  eating,  the  greater  danger  of  starva- 
tion in  not  eating.  Many  men  are  drowned  in 
svi^imming,  many  more  men  are  drowned  be- 
cause they  do  not  know  how  to  s*vim.  Hazard 
is  the  law  of  life,  a  law  which  becomes  more 
exacting  as  life  rises  into  its  higher  forms.  Life 
itself  binds  up  all  hazards,  and  is  itself  the 
supreme  hazard.  He  only  never  risks  who  never 
lives,  and  he  who  incurs  none  of  the  hazards  of 
life  performs  none  of  its  duties. 

But  if  ignorance  were  innocence  and  safety, 
the  features  of  our  time  on  which  we  have 
dw^elt,  show  that  ignorance  here  is  impossible. 
The  choice  is  not  between  ignorance  and  some 


NECESSITY   OF   DISCUSSING   MATERIALISM.       29 

sort  of  knowledge  of  Materialism,  but  between 
intelligent  and  correct  impressions  and  false 
ones.  Which  shall  the  minds  that  are  forming 
have :  a  knowledge  of  Materialism  in  all  its 
strength,  without  the  antidote,  or  of  Materialism 
falsely  understated,  with  the  possibility,  almost 
certainty,  that  they  will  one  day  see  that  it  has 
been  understated,  and  rush  to  the  conclusion 
that  its  opponents  did  not  dare  to  let  the  truth 
about  it  be  known,  or  shall  we  have  Materialism 
fairly  presented  and  fairly  met?  If  the  last  be 
the  best  course,  then  this  volume  meets  a  real 
want,  for  in  it  Strauss  presents  the  plea  for 
Materialism  more  attractively  than  it  has  ever 
been  presented,  and  in  it  Ulrici  annihilates 
that  plea. 

Especially  is  it  the  duty  of  educated  men  to 
know  the  grounds  of  the  most  dangerous  and 
seductive  error  of  our  time,  and  to  be  master  of 
the  arguments  by  which  that  error  is  overthrown. 
The  educated  man  ought  to  feel  that  without 
this  knowledge  he  is  not  really  educated.  But 
if  he  be  indifferent  to  it  for  himself,  he  should 
possess  it  for  the  benefit  of  others.  No  man 
liveth  to  himself,  least  of  all  the  man  of  culture. 
He  is  of  the  class  who  are  to  be  guides  in  their 
generation,  and  he  must  be  willing  to  accept  the 
responsibilities,  and  incur  the  risks  of  his  voca- 


30  INTRODUCTION. 

tion.  The  physician  cannot  heal  contagious 
diseases  without  hazarding  contagion.  To  the 
scholar  and  thinker  others  will  come.  The 
weakness  of  the  thinker  is  the  weakness  of  the 
seeker.  The  is^norance  of  the  scholar  is  the 
hopeless  ignorance  of  the  learners,  as,  on  the 
other  hand,  his  knowledge  will  be  their  knowl- 
edge, his  strength  of  assurance  their  conviction. 
It  will  to  many  be  enough  that  he  understands 
the  problem,  if  the^^  do  not.  The  true  scholar 
and  thinker  is,  at  last,  the  last  power.  In  the 
world  of  thought  the  many  decide,  but  the  few 
decide  the  many.  It  is  as  in  most  free  govern- 
ments, the  voters  are  a  democracy,  the  rulers 
an  aristocracy. 

The  mere  seeming  to  avoid  fair  discussion, 
does  more  mischief  than  a  real  acquaintance 
with  Materialism  possibly  can.  To  be  cowardly 
is  to  be  beaten  without  a  battle.  Materialism, 
with  the  arrogance  common  to  all  error,  claims 
to  be  invincible.  If  it  be  not  attacked,  or  its 
attack  be  declined,  its  explanation  is  invariably 
found,  in  the  fears  of  its  antagonists. 


APPEARANCE   OF   STRAUSS's   BOOK.  31 


RECEKT  DISCUSSIONS.     APPEARANCE  OF  STRATJSS'S 

BOOK. 

The  questions  associated  with  Materialism 
have  been  discussed  most  earnestly  and  fully 
among  the  nations  which  may  fairly  claim  the 
intellectual  leadership  of  the  world.  England, 
France  and  America  have  names  of  renown  on 
both  sides  of  the  question.  Holland  has  thinkers 
whose  contributions  to  this  single  department 
of  thought,  would  reward  the  man  who  acquired 
its  language  solely  to  read  them.  It  is  in  Ger- 
many, however,  we  find  the  treatment  of  these 
questions  conducted  with  the  most  distinguished 
ability.  Whether  we  ask  for  the  most  popular 
or  the  most  profound  works  for  Materialism,  or 
against  it,  it  is  Germany  which  furnishes  them. 
On  the  one  side  she  has  had  Feuerbach,  Mole- 
SCHOTT,  BucHNER,  and  VoGT,  as  the  chief  advo- 
cates of  Materialism;  on  the  other  Schaller, 

TiTTMANN,  FrOHSCHAMMER,  J.  H.  FiCHTE,  FaBRI, 

BoHNER,  and  Ulrici,  as  its  opponents,  and  now 
within  a  year  past  a  host  of  able  writers,  old 
and  new,  has  sprung  to  arms,  on  a  new  declara- 
tion of  war. 

This  latest  and  sharpest  struggle  to  which  the 
Materialistic  controversy  has  led  is  that  in  which 
the  offensive  was  taken  by  David  Friedrich 


32  INTRODUCTION. 

Strauss.  The  ^' great  critic/'  as  his  friends 
loved  to  consider  him,  and  as  he  loved  to  con- 
sider himself,  brought  to  religion  the  sort  of 
criticism  which  the  Vandals  brought  to  art,  the 
criticism  of  barbarous,  ruthless  demolition,  the 
savage  iconoclasm,  which  spends  its  fury  on  the 
beauty  it  can  neither  comprehend  nor  feel. 
Among  the  secrets  of  Strauss's  power  has  been 
that  by  skilful  following  he  seemed  to  lead  the 
tendencies  of  his  time,  that  he  wrote  in  a  style 
admitted  to  be  classic  in  form,  and  that  he  had 
a  plausible  superficiality,  which  made  the  indo- 
lent and  half-informed  reader  satisfied  that  he 
saw  to  the  bottom  of  the  subject,  because  he 
saw  to  the  bottom  of  the  book.  More  than  all 
he  was  indebted  to  a  certain  tempered  extrava- 
gance, a  power  of  fanaticism  under  a  form  of 
rationality.  He  gave  himself  with  inexorable 
concentration  in  each  case  to  a  leading  idea, 
never  his  own — he  has  not  added  a  fact  to 
knowledge  nor  a  principle  to  speculation — and 
on  this  idea  he  has  worked  with  a  unity  of  aim, 
an  industry  of  accumulation  both  of  serviceable 
fact  and  illustration,  which  has  made  his  pre- 
sentation irresistible  to  many  minds.  That 
Strauss  was  at  once  so  earnest  and  so  cool,  so 
much  the  moulder  of  the  passions  of  others  and 
the  controller  of  his  own,  made  him  one  of  the 


APPEARANCE   OF  STRAUSS's   BOOK.  33 

great  powers  of  his  age.  Essentially  frivolous, 
both  intellectually  and  ethically,  he  yet  gives 
the  reader  an  impression  of  earnestness  and 
moral  feeling,  and  thus  influences  those  who, 
in  the  happy  phrase  of  Philippson,  "  confound 
"  the  evidences  of  truthfulness  with  the  evi- 
"  dences  of  truth." 

This  man,  not,  we  believe,  without  the  order 
of  Providence,  came  forth,  in  the  evening  of 
his  long  life,  with  a  sort  of  summary,  a  canon- 
ical epitome,  of  the  results  of  all  his  learning, 
and  of  all  his  speculation.  It  was  the  finality 
of  a  brilliant  career,  in  which  inordinate  vanity 
had  been  wonderfully  gratified.  The  man  who 
had  tried  to  shake  all  forms  of  religion,  pro- 
posed, in  his  modesty,  a  compensation  for  them 
all  in  a  discovery  of  his  own.  The  great  foe  of 
all  creeds,  and  most  of  all  of  the  old  creed, 
proposed  a  new  creed,  which  was  but  an  old 
creed,  forgotten  into  newness.  After  trying 
to  rob  all  men  of  their  faith,  he  came  forth  with 
a  confession  of  his  own  faith ;  a  faith  in  which 
conscious  matter  reverenced  and  worshipped 
unconscious  matter;  in  which  reason  bowed  at 
the  altar  of  the  Unreason  which  had  given  it 
being;  a  faith  without  Grod  or  Providence,  with- 
out spirit,  freedom,  or  accountability;  a  faith 
devoid  of  a  recognition  of  creation,  redemption, 


34  INTRODUCTION. 

or  sanctification,  of  sin  or  of  salvation.  It  had 
no  heaven  to  desire,  no  hell  to  shun.  Its  last 
enemy  is  not  death,  but  immortality;  its  goal 
is  extinction.  The  onl}^  "  Incarnation  "  of  which 
it  knows  is  *'  the  Incarnation  of  the  ape.''  Like 
the  universe  it  imagined,  this  faith  is  uncreated 
and  self-existent,  an  effect  without  a  cause,  a  re- 
sult without  an  antecedent,  an  end  without  aim, 
plan,  design,  or  means.  This  is  the  ''  new  faith '' 
of  Strauss,  to  which  the  new  book  is  devoted. 
It  is  not  w^onderful  that  such  a  book  from  such 
a  man  attracted  extraordinary  attention,  that  it 
ran  rapidly  through  a  number  of  editions,  and 
was  eagerly  read  by  thousands.  It  owed  some- 
thing to  the  virtues  of  its  manner,  its  literary 
graces,  its  felicitous  sophistries;  it  owed  much 
more  to  the  vices  of  its  matter.  A  few  came 
to  its  perusal  in  the  hope  of  learning  some- 
thing; many  took  it  up  to  find  in  it  flattery  for 
the  convictions  they  already  held.  Most  readers 
aimed  at  no  more  than  the  gratification  of  curi- 
osity. The  first  class  were  bitterly  disappointed ; 
the  second  found  that  the  sweetness  of  the  flat- 
tery had  some  bitter  qualifications ;  the  last 
found  the  gratification  they  sought,  for  the 
book  is  really  one  of  the  strangest  in  the  annals 
of  Literature,  and  will  be  longest  remembered 
as  one  of  its  curiosities. 


STRAUSS'S   REVIEWERS.  35 


STRAUSS'S  REVIEWERS. 


The  intrinsic  interest  of  the  questions  dis- 
cussed, the  antecedent  general  excitement  of 
the  public  mind  in  regard  to  them,  the  great- 
ness of  Strauss's  name,  the  marvellous  suc- 
cess of  his  book  in  interesting  men;  and  yet 
more,  the  audacious  and  dangerous  character  of 
its  doctrines,  the  arrogance  of  its  assertions, 
the  Ultramontanism  of  its  unbelief,  and  of  its 
denunciation  of  doctrines  in  opposition  to  it, — 
Strauss  was  at  once  the  Ecumenical  Council  of 
the  "  We,^^  which  proclaimed  the  dogma  of  the 
atheistic  infallibility,  and  the  Pio  Nino  who 
for  the  present  embodied  it — the  boasts  of  in- 
dependence in  connection  with  the  servility  of 
its  adhesions,  the  ultraisms  of  radicalism  on 
which  it  built  the  ultraisms  of  conservatism, 
the  all-destroying  infidelity  on  which  it  reared 
its  world-challenging  highest  faith — all  these 
thing's  led  to  an  extraordinarv  number  of  no- 
tices  of  it.  Scarcely  one  of  them,  even  from  the 
number  of  Strauss's  warmest  admirers,  gave 
the  book  unmingled  commendation.  The  great 
mass  of  notices  coming  from  thinkers  of  various 
schools — Israelite  and  Christian,  orthodox,  ra- 
tionalistic and  old  Catholic;  from  divines,  men 
of  science,  philosophers  and  practical  men — with 


36  INTRODUCTION. 

a  wonderful  uniformity,  condemned  the  prin- 
ciples of  the  book,  exposed  its  falsities  of  argu- 
ment and  its  errors  in  fact,  and  showed  that  all 
the  moral  relief  which  any  of  its  better  views 
offered,  were  in  utter  conflict  with  the  funda- 
mental principles  of  the  speculations  on  which 
they  professedly  rested.  Few  books  have  at- 
tracted so  many  readers  as  Strauss's  last  book; 
very  few  have  disappointed  and  disgusted  so 
many. 

Nothing,  perhaps,  could  give  a  more  vivid 
sense  of  the  affluence  of  German  learning,  and 
the  vigor  of  German  thinking,  than  to  notice 
what  an  amount  of  both  has  been  called  forth 
by  this  single  book  of  Strauss.  The  catalogue 
of  its  literature  would  make  a  volume,  and  this 
literature,  in  some  shape  or  other,  takes  in 
nearly  every  great  question  of  the  day,  relig- 
ious, literary,  educational,  philosophical,  politi- 
cal and  practical. 

For  reasons  of  various  kinds,  some  of  the  re- 
viewers of  Strauss  take  a  special  prominence. 
MoRiTZ  Carriers  is  distinguished  as  a  historian 
of  art,  and  a  writer  on  aesthetics.  Huber,  Pro- 
fessor of  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Mu- 
nich, Knoodt,  Zierngebl  and  Michelis,  are 
"Old  Catholics ;''  and  it  is  a  remarkable  fea- 
ture of  the  time  that  the  "  Old  Catholics''  have 


STRAUSS'S   REVIEWERS.  37 

been  represented  with  such  special  ability  in 
the  battle  against  Strauss. 

Among  philosophers  by  profession  who  have 
borne  a  part  in  the  discussion  may  be  mentioned 
Immanuel  Hermann  Fichte,  who  in  his  latest 
work,  "  The  Theistic  View  of  the  World,"  has 
presented  an  account  of  the  grand  problems  of 
the  speculation  of  our  day,  with  much  that 
bears  specially  upon  Strauss. 

Alfred  Dove  is  editor  of  the  periodical  ''  Im 
neuer  Reich,''  and  has  won  distinction  as  an  es- 
sayist. Dr.  Weis,  the  chemist,  is  author  of 
"  Antimaterialism,"  in  which  he  has  shown 
marked  ability  as  an  investigator  of  nature  and 
as  a  philosophical  thinker.  Frenzel  has  writ- 
ten an  article  under  the  title — suggested  by  the 
Edda — "  Twilight  of  the  Gods,"  an  article  which 
NiPPOLD  pronounces  "  classical." 

One  of  the  very  ablest  replies  to  Strauss  is 
from  the  pen  of  Philippson,  the  representative 
of  reformatory  Judaism,  widely  known  by  his 
numerous  vigorous  and  brilliant  works.  Haus- 
rath  has  written  on  the  New  Testament  his- 
tory. Sporri  is  of  the  school  of  "  liberal  Protes- 
tant "  theology.  Jijrgen  Bona  Meyer  is  Pro- 
fessor of  Philosophy  at  Bonn. 

The  latest  works  from  German  hands  which 
have    reached   us    are   Frohschammer's   ''The 

2 


38  INTRODUCTION. 

New  Science  and  the  New  Faith,"  Ziegler's 
"Reply  to  Huber/'  and  Stutz's  Work  (1874). 

In  America,  the  discussion  has  been  opened 
by  reviews  in  the  April  number  of  the  ''  Meth- 
odist Quarterly/'  and  of  the  "Presbyterian 
Quarterly.'^  The  latter  article  is  by  Prof. 
Henry  B.  Smith.  He  designs  to  follow  it  by  a 
further  discussion,  but  as  it  stands,  it  establishes 
a  claim  to  a  place  among  the  best  things  which 
the  theme  has  called  forth. 

Holland  is  very  strongly  represented  in  Eau- 
WENHOFF  and  Scholten,  professors  at  Leyden, 
two  of  the  ablest  writers  of  our  day.  Yera,  of 
Naples,  has  reviewed  Strauss  at  great  length, 
from  the  Hegelian  point  of  view,  of  which 
Strauss  was  originally  an  ardent  supporter, 
and  which,  indeed,  furnishes  the  basis  for  his 
critical  works.  Mariano  has  reviewed  (Rome, 
1874)  both  Strauss  and  Vera. 

In  England  Sterling  has  reviewed  Strauss 
in  the  "Athenaeum,''  June,  1873.  An  article 
by  Scholten  appears  in  "  The  Theological  Re- 
view," May,  1873. 

NiPPOLD  has  given  an  account  of  the  literature 
called  forth  by  the  controversy,  but  even  his  ap- 
pendix, dated  August  11th,  1873,  was  too  early 
to  foreclose  the  bibliography  of  the  subject. 


REVIEWS   OF   STRAUSS.  39 


P0II!^TS   OF   ITSTTEREST  IN    THE  REVIEWS   OF  STRAUSS. 

Among  the  many  points  of  interest  in  these 
reviews,  one  of  the  most  striking  is  the  esti- 
mates, general  and  particular,  which  they  put 
upon  Strauss.  They  nearly  without  exception 
show  that  no  antecedent  aversion  is  the  cause 
of  their  dislike  of  this  book,  but  that  on  the 
contrary  they  were  disposed  to  honor  and  mag- 
nify him. 

"  The  overwhelming  impression  made  by  the 
"book  is  due  to  the  undeniable  talent  of  the 
"  author,  to  the  actual  beauty  of  portions  of  it, 
"especially  of  the  tributes  to  the  great  poets 
"and  musicians  of  German v,  and  to  the  nov- 
"elty  of  the  idea  of  bringing  into  unity  the  re- 
"  suits  of  theological  criticism  and  of  the  latest 
"investigations  of  nature,  and  of  welding  them 
"  together  in  a  systematic  view  of  the  world  and 
"of  life."*  "That  in  the  darling  controversy 
"of  the  hour  this  book  has  attracted  almost 
"more  notice  than  all  the  others  too:ether,  is  a 
"clear  proof  that  Strauss  represents  one  of  the 
"great  powers  in  the  realms  of  mind. "f  "The 
"first  question  which  the  book  forced  upon  us 
"was,  how  so  acute  a  thinker,  so  practiced  a 

■^  Rauwenhoff.  '        |  Nippold. 


40  INTRODUCTION. 


a 


writer,  so  finished  and  cautious  a  critic,  could 
^' lower  himself  to  the  position  of  a  blindly 
''credulous  train-bearer  of  the  most  vulgar  Ma- 
"terialism;  at  a  time,  too,  when  this  view  is 
''beginning  to  decline,  when  even  the  more 
"acute  physiologists,  in  the  most  explicit  terms 
"and  with  a  full  statement  of  their  reasons,  are 
"abandoning  the  materialistic  explanation  of 
"the  phenomena  of  mind.  The  solution  is 
"found  in  the  fact  that  Strauss  is  and  remains 
"a  combatant  in  the  sphere  of  theology,  and 
"seeks  subsidiary  troops  from  every  direction 
"to  sustain  him  there."*  Beyschlag,  Philipp- 
SON,  Frenzel,  and  others  pay  tribute  to  the 
personal  honorableness  of  Strauss,  but  other 
critics,  as  W.  Lang,  point  to  special  instances 
of  unfair  dealing  in  his  book.  "Of  construct- 
"ive  reason  he  shows  but  a  feeble  trace;  of  the 
"heart,  in  what  it  truly  holds,  and  of  its  meas- 
"ureless  importance  for  the  race,  he  seems  to 
"have  not  a  glimpse.  In  the  scientific  part  of 
"his  book  he  keeps  house  entirely  with  what 
"he  borrows,  all  his  creative  power  and  origi- 
"nality  deserts  him,  and  if  he  were  the  critic  of 
"  the  book,  instead  of  being  its  author,  he  would 
"be  the  first  to  expose  its  weaknesses.     When 

*  I.  H.  Fichte. 


REVIEWS   OF   STRAUSS.  41 

'we  get  out  of  the  woods  of  the  criticism  of 
'Christianitv,  and  down  into  the  field  of  re- 
Migion  at  large,  we  see  Strauss  at  once  desti- 
'tate  of  resources  of  his  own,  and  going  into 
'consultation  with  Hume,  Epictetus,  and  Lud- 
'wio  Feuerbach.  We  frankly  confess  our 
'opinion  that  for  a  German  thinker  he  employs 
'such  clumsy  weapons  that  he  must  himself 
'feel  ashamed  of  them.  On  what  a  feeble  pub- 
'lic  he  must  have  counted.  He  will  not  terrify 
'us  with  his  epithet  'old-fashioned.'  His  own 
'imaginary  counter-proofs  have  already  become 
'old-fashioned.  Strauss  calls  his  views  'new.' 
'They  are  not  new,  they  are  merely  the  newest 
'  manifestation  of  a  very  ancient  tendency  of  the 
'mind.  They  are  old,  and  have  long  been 
'passed  by.  In  vain  does  he  cling  to  Kant; 
'Voltaire  and  Karl  Voot  have  grasped  him, 
'and  drag  him  after  them;  vain  is  his  fright  at 
'Schopenhauer  and  Von  Hartman;  that  he 
'does  not  yield  himself  to  them  is  to  be  put  to 
'the  score  of  his  weakness."* 

"That  a  deaf  man  should  not  undertake  to 
'write  the  history  of  music,  that  a  blind  man 
'should  not  propose  to  give  the  world  a  history 
'of  art,  would  not  be  disputed,  and  yet  there  be 

•^  Philippson. 


42  INTRODUCTION. 

''  curious  people  who  think  it  just  the  thing  that 
''conscious,  unblushing,  systematic  irreligious- 
"ness  should  write  the  life  of  Jesus.  Is  it  pos- 
''sible  for  a  man  to  write  the  history  of  a  move- 
"  ment  of  the  soul,  with  which  he  feels  no  con- 
''genialit^^,  but  toward  which  he  takes  a  purely 
''negative  attitude?  Can  a  man  who  regards 
"religion  as  the  fantastic  product  of  the  addled 
"mind,  even  form  a  judgment  whether  the 
"history  of  a  founder  of  a  religion  is  a  thing 
"that  could  possibly  be  written  ?"* 

Strauss's  comparison  of  w^hat  claims  to  be 
Christianity  in  the  present  with  the  Christianity^ 
of  the  past,  leads  Dove  to  say:  "We  may  in- 
"deed  be  drawn  in  this  way  to  deny  with 
"  Strauss  the  claim  of  the  present  to  the  Chris- 
"tian  name,  or  we  may,  with  Feuerbach,  de- 
"ride  it  as  a  'dissolute,  characterless,  comfort- 
'"able,  belles-lettres,  coquettish,  epicurean 
"'Christianity.'  But  is  this  a  historic  way  of 
"treating  the  matter?  Would  it  not  be  just 
"as  fair  to  assume  as  the  classic  standard  of 
"the  Germanic,  the  German  character  at  a  par- 
"ticular  period,  say,  for  example,  the  time  of 
"Otto  the  Great,  and  allow  us  Germans  of  to- 
"day  to  pass,  at  the  very  highest,  for  nothing 

^  Hausrath. 


REVIEWS  OF  STRAUSS.  43 

"better  than  ^dissolute,  characterless,  comfort- 
"^able,  belles-lettres,  coquettish,  epicurean  Ger- 
"'mans?"' 

That  so  many  of  Strauss's  old  admirers 
should  take  up  arms  against  him,  is  explained 
in  some  measure  by  the  fact  that  his  candid 
statement  of  the  logical  finality  of  his  move- 
ment has  been  very  alarming  to  a  large  class  of 
them.  The  answer  of  this  class  to  the  question, 
*''  Are  we  Christians  still  ?"  has  constantly  been 
that  thej"  are  Christians  of  the  purest  and  the 
best.  They  do  not  receive  Christ  in  his  personal 
claims;  they  acknowledge  in  him  nothing 
superhuman ;  they  repudiate  alike  the  miracles 
wrought  by  him,  and  the  miraculous  events 
which  are  parts  of  his  own  history,  but  all  the 
more  in  the  power  of  the  etherealized,  unembar- 
rassed residuum,  can  they  soar  as  Christians. 
They  repudiate  a  religion  about  Christ  and  con- 
fine themselves  to  the  religion  of  Christ ;  they, 
in  a  word,  claim  to  be  of  the  same  religion  with 
Christ;  he  is  at  best  a  mere  primus  inter  peaces. 
And  yet  he  is  hardly  that — beyond  the  credulous 
adherents  of  the  old  faith,  they  are  veritable 
Christians,  because  they  have  improved  upon 
the  Teacher,  and  are  more  Christian  than  Christ 
himself.  But  Strauss  abandons  them  in  this 
claim,  and  insists  that  it  is  dishonorable  for  him- 


44  INTRODUCTION. 

self  and  those  who  stand  with  him  in  his  criti- 
cisms of  Christ  and  Christianity,  to  call  them- 
selves Christians.  He  shows  that  Christianity 
in  its  very  essence  involves  the  personal  claims 
of  Christ;  that  to  take  the  name  of  the  dimly 
seen  enthusiast  of  Galilee,  and  yet  deny  the 
miracles,  without  the  claims  of  which  for  him, 
that  name  would  never  have  reached  us,  is 
absurd.  Jesus  might  have  been  all  of  truest 
and  best  that  the  strongest  claim  for  him  has 
ever  asserted,  "  and  yet,"  says  Strauss,  "  his 
"  doctrines  would  have  been  like  leaves  driven 
"  and  scattered  before  the  wind,  had  not  a 
"  fond  faith  in  his  resurrection  bound  together 
''  these  leaves  in  one  compact  mass."*  Strauss 
says,  in  eftect.  We  have  outgrown  our  old  posi- 
tion. From  knowing  little  of  Jesus,  we  have 
advanced  till  we  know  nothing ;  to  pretend  to 
know  anything  carries  us  back  to  the  old  ortho- 
dox position  which  claims  to  know  everything. 
The  logic  of  the  blind  old  faith  is  with  the 
Creeds  of  the  churches,  the  logic  of  the  new 
faith  is  Materialism  and  Atheism. 

Strauss  who  commenced  by  killing  the  old 
school  of  Rationalists  with  his  myths,  ends  with 
killing  the  whole  brood  of  the  mythical  Chris- 

^  Alt.  u.  Neu.  Glaub.  Sechst.  Aufl.,  73. 


REVIEWS   OF  STRAUSS.  45 

tians  with  his  ''new  faith.''  The  fine  line  he 
once  drew  between  the  permanent  and  tran- 
sient in  Christianity  has  vanished.  He  has 
got  the  whole  in  one  neck  now,  and  the  blow 
falls.  Everything  in  Christianity  is  transient. 
The  insatiate  old  critic,  born  as  he  claims,  to  be 
a  ruthless  destroyer,  having  disposed  of  every- 
thing else,  eats  his  own  words,  and  Saturn-like 
ends  the  scene  by  devouring  his  own  ofi:spring. 
The  weeping  and  protestations  of  these  hapless 
children  are  the  attestations  of  their  reluctance 
to  vanish  within  the  expanding  jaws  of  this  tre- 
mendous old  anthropophagite. 

That  Strauss  greatly  miscalculated  the  power 
of  his  leadership  in  this  new  movement  is  cer- 
tain. "The  'We,'"  says  Frenzel,  "furnish,  I 
"  fear,  the  matter  of  the  philosopher's  first  decep- 
"  tion.  Certainly  a  large  number  of  cultivated 
"  persons,  and  these  form  the  only  class  brought 
"  into  account  here,  will  follow  his  first  steps;  but 
"  with  every  step  of  his  advance,  the  number  of 
"  his  adherents,  or,  rather  we  should  style  them, 
"  those  who  share  his  views,  more  and  more 
"  melts  away.  Some  of  them  will  hold  fast  to  this 
"  point,  others  to  that,  in  the  old  faith.  There 
"  are  those  who  will  not  abandon  the  immortality 
"  of  the  soul  in  some  shape ;  others  will  not  find 
"  the  Darwino-Yogto-Straussian  primal  ape  at 


46  INTRODUCTION. 

''all  to  their  taste.  When  Strauss  reaches  the 
''goal  of  his  views  of  religion,  his  view  of  the 
"  universe,  he  will  find  very  few  with  him,  and 
"  when  out  of  theory  he  springs  into  the  prac- 
"  tical,  making  his  leap  from  religion  into  poli- 
"tics,  he  will  find  himself  alone."  "  Philoso- 
"  phy  equally  with  religion,  rests  at  last  on  the 
"  unfathomable.  No  man  hath  seen  the  aveng- 
"  ing  God  of  the  Old  Testament,  or  God  the 
"Father,  revealed  in  the  New.  But  neither 
"  has  any  man  ever  taken  a  survey  of  Strauss's 
"  universe.  The  one  equally  with  the  other  is  a 
conception.  Adam  the  first  man  lives  only  in 
the  Mosaic  record,  but  does,  perchance,  Dar- 
win's primal  ape  have  a  better  hold  on  life  ? 
"  He  too  has  vanished  and  left  no  trace.  The 
"  theologians  are  enthusiasts  for  Adam,  the 
"  zoologists  are  enthusiasts  for  the  ape.  That  is 
"  the  total  difterence. 

"  If  Strauss  imagines  that  he  is  actually  able, 
"  as  he  wishes,  to  establish  his  new  faith  and 
"  suppress  Christianity,  he  seems  to  have  fallen 
"into  a  fatal  illusion — the  illusion  of  Voltaire 
"and  Diderot.  They  imas-ined  that  because 
they  were  unbelievers  themselves,  the  time 
must  come  when  nobody  would  believe,  the 
time  when  all  men  would  be  philosophers. 
Nevertheless  with  the  whole  development  of 


REVIEWS   OF   STRAUSS.  47 

"humanity  lying  before  us,  we  see  a  vanishing 
"  minority  in  the  path  of  philosophy,  an  over- 
''  whelming  mjijority  following  after  religion. 
"  For  whole  ages  together  philosophy'  has  been 
"  dumb ;  in  no  age  has  the  voice  of  religion  been 
"silenced." 

Strauss  is  charged  by  a  number  of  the  re- 
viewers with  ignorance,  or  persistent  ignoring  of 
what  is  strongest  in  opposition  to  his  own  views. 
He  and  his  school  are  blamed  with  appealing  to 
authority  as  arbitrarily  as  the  most  implicit 
orthodoxy  does.  Vogt  and  Moleschott  are 
exalted  to  the  place  of  Church  Fathers.  Froh- 
SCHAMMER,  after  commending  Strauss's  early 
labors,  goes  on  to  say :  "  The  more  do  we  re- 
"  gret  that  Strauss  has  now  gone  to  the  op- 
"  posite  extreme.  He  has  forsaken  the  purely 
"  human,  rational,  and  ideal  position  for  which 
"  he  battled  against  the  supernatural  and  irra- 
"  tional  position  of  Faith,  and  has  fallen  into 
"  a  subhuman,  materialistic  theory,  as  ground- 
"  less  and  pernicious  as  the  one  he  rejected. 
"  Yet  to  supply  the  defects  of  this  very  theory, 
"  he  puts  forth  by  way  of  enactment  his  own 
"  strength  of  faith,  that  sort  of  faith  which  he 
"  has  so  critically  and  decidedly  refused  to  allow 
"  for  the  benefit  of  anything  else. 

"  Our  regret  is  the  greater  and  more  just, 


48  INTRODUCTION. 

''  since  we  are  threatened  with  the  formation  of 
''  a  new  priestcraft,  a  priestcraft  of  Atheism  and 
"  Materialism,  which  will  be  no  less  fanatical 
''  against  those  who  cannot  accept  it  than  '  Su- 
"  pernaturalism'  has  been;  which  will  demand 
''just  as  blind  a  faith  even  for  its  utterly  ground- 
"  less  assertions  as  this  has  done,  and  will 
"  throughout  proceed  in  just  as  uncritical  a 
"  way.  Any  one  acquainted  with  the  writings 
"  of  the  most  renowned  representatives  of  Ma- 
"  terialism,  will  readily  perceive  the  truth  of 
"  this  statement.  He  will  not  fail  to  observe 
"  that  this  tendency  shows  a  common  affinity 
"  and  a  parallelism  with  that  old  credulous 
"  Supernaturalism,  in  the  ignorant  supercil- 
"  iousness  and  blind  depreciation  it  displays 
"  toward  philosophy,  and  in  its  disposition  to 
"  treat  all  that  is  ideal  in  feeling  and  judgment 
"  as  useless  '  drivel'  or  empty  fancy.'' 

Strauss  is  censured  for  doing  violence  to  his 
national  affinities,  which  ought  to  have  been 
with  men  like  Fichte  the  younger,  Weisse, 
LoTZE,  and  the  German  philosophers  in  gen- 
eral. He  has  renounced  them  all  in  favor  of 
the  wisdom  of  the  French  Encyclopedists,  and 
of  the  "  Systeme  de  la  Nature."  "  God  and 
"  the  Universe,"  says  Carriere,  "  are  not 
"  merely  '  two  equivalents  for  the  same  thing,' 


STRAUSS'S   INCONSISTENCY.  49 

"  and  the  total  result  of  the  entire  modern 
"  philosophy  in  regard  to  the  nature  of  God, 
''  does  not  end  in  this,  as  Strauss  assures  us  it 
"  does.  Baader,  Schelling,  Krause,  taught 
"  the  personality  of  God.  Lotze,  Lazarus,  of 
''  the  school  of  Herbart,  Weisse,  and  Fichte 
"  the  younger,  coming  rather  from  the  direction 
''  of  Hegel,  Trendlenburg,  Ulrici,  Wirth, 
''  Ritter,  Huber,  and  very  many  other  thinkers, 
"  have  devoted  comprehensive  works  to  the 
''  establishment  of  a  specific  apprehension  of 
''  this  question  very  different  from  that  which 
"  Strauss  represents.  Though  Strauss  will  not 
"  look  at  these  books,  they  are  none  the  less 
"  there.'*  Carriere  specially  mentions  Ulrici's 
"  God  and  Nature,"  as  a  book  to  which  Strauss 
ought  to  have  had  regard. 


strauss's  inconsistency  with  his  earlier 
position. 

That  Strauss  has  departed  from  his  earlier 
position  is  acknowledged  by  all  his  reviewers. 
The  one  set  charges  it  on  him  as  the  change  of 
an  inconsistent  man.  The  other,  which  includes 
his  most  determined  friends  and  his  extremest 
foes,  unites  in  declaring  that  his  present  posi- 
tion  is    but   the   change   of    ripening   and   of 


50  INTRODUCTION. 

more  matured  consistency.  Strauss  liad  said  : 
*'  Where  shall  we  find  in  such  beauty  as  we  lind 
"it  in  Jesus,  that  mirroring  purity  of  soul,  which 
"  the  fury  of  the  storm  may  agitate  but  cannot 
"  cloud  ?  Where  has  there  been  so  grand  an 
^'  idea,  so  restless  an  activity,  so  exalted  a  sacri- 
*' lice  for  it  as  in  Jesus?  Who  has  been  the 
"founder  of  a  work  which  has  endowed  with 
"  as  rich  treasures,  in  as  high  a  degree,  the 
"masses  of  men  and  nations  through  the  long 
"ages,  as  the  Tvork  which  bears  the  name  of 
"  Christ  ?  As  little  as  mankind  can  be  without 
religion,  so  little  can  they  be  without  Christ. 
.  .  .  And  this  Christ,  as  inseparable  from  the 
supremest  shaping  of  religion,  is  historical 
not  mythical;  he  is  an  individual,  not  a  bare 
"  svmbol." 

From  the  Strauss  of  1839,  the  transition  is  so 
great  to  the  Strauss  of  1872,  that  his  English 
translator  (apparently  a  novice,  furnished  with 
a  very  imperfect  dictionary),  has  not  dared 
fairly  to  reproduce  all  of  his  coarseness,  in  con- 
nection with  the  name  of  Christ.  If  Strauss 
knew  how  to  develop  legitimately  from  the 
point  he  abandoned  to  the  point  he  has  reached, 
the  logic  is  resistless  that  there  is  no  consistent 
position  between  the  Christ  of  the  old  faith  and 
the  Materialistic  Atheism  of  the  new.     But  if 


THE  GREAT  PHYSICISTS.  51 

the  Strauss  of  the  inferences  be  illogical,  how 
stall  we  regard  the  Strauss  of  the  premises  ? 

THE  GREAT  PHYSICISTS. 

The  nature  of  the  theme  and  of  the  time  has 
led  to  a  large  summoning  into  court  of  the  men 
of  the  past,  and  still  more  of  the  present,  whose 
names   add   lustre    to    the    physical    sciences. 
Among  the  dead,  the  names   most  frequently 
cited  are  those  of  Aristotle,  Newton,  Kant, 
La  Place,  Reimarus,  Lamarck,  Cuvier,  Oken, 
LiEBia,    Johannes     Mijller,   Eisenlohr    and 
Rudolf  Wagner.     Humboldt's  remark,  made 
the  more  telling  by  his  general  admiration  of 
Strauss,  is  quoted:  "  What  has  not  pleased  me 
"  in  Strauss,  is  the  levity  he  displays  in  the 
"  sphere  of  natural  history,  in  his  readiness  to 
"  find  the  origination  of  the  organic  out  of  the 
^'inorganic,  and  the  formation  of  man  himself 
"  out  of  the  primeval  slime  of  Chaldea."   Agas- 
siz's  influence  does  not  seem  to  have  been  im- 
paired even    by  Bijchner's   intolerable   impu- 
dence in  asserting  that  his  anti-Darwinian  views 
were  an  accommodation  to  the  Puritan  atmo- 
sphere  which    surrounded    him    in   America. 
Among  the  names  of  living  authors  we  may 
mention  a  few  which  are  specially  prominent. 


52  INTRODUCTION. 

Yon  Baer,  of  Konigsberg,  is  distinguislied  in 
the  History  of  Development  and  in  Zootomy. 
Clausius,  of  Bonn,  is  renowned  as  a  physi- 
cist, especially  in  the  establishment  of  the  doc- 
trine of  heat  as  a  mode  of  motion.  For  his 
merits  in  this  he  received  the  great  Huygen's 
gold  medal  in  1870.  Bonders,  of  Utrecht,  is 
illustrious  as  a  physiologist  and  oculist,  and  is 
the  founder  of  a  great  system  of  ophthalmology. 
He  is  ''an  investigator  of  acknowledged  geni- 
*'  alit}^  thoroughness  and  many-sidedness.  His 
"  very  numerous  writings  are  distinguished  by 
"  clearness  and  elegance.^'  He  was  the  first  to 
apply  the  principle  of  the  conservation  of  force 
to  the  animal  organism.  Du  Bois-Reymond, 
of  Berlin,  pupil  of  Johannes  Mijller,  holds 
the  chair  of  his  master.  His  renown  is  very 
great  in  the  general  field  of  natural  sciences, 
but  is  pre-eminently  so  in  "  animal  electricity." 
Helmholiz,  of  Berlin,  occupies  a  high  posi- 
tion among  the  German  physicists,  and  he  owes 
his  distinction  in  no  small  measure  to  the  phil- 
osophical spirit  of  his  investigations.  He  has 
united  the  most  complete,  many-sided,  and  thor- 
ough elaboration  of  the  individual  minutise  with 
a  range  of  view  v^hich  takes  in  the  whole  in  its 
greatness.  By  physiological  investigations  he 
has   been    carried   to   results   which,  at   many 


THE  GREAT  PHYSICISTS.  53 

points,  touch  those  which  Kant  reached  by 
purely  metaphysical  processes.  Lotze,  of  Got- 
tingen,  is  one  of  the  most  modest,  and  yet  one 
of  the  profoundest  and  most  brilliant  of  that 
grandest  school  of  thinkers  who  are  great  both 
in  physical  science  and  in  metaphysics.  His 
'' Mikrokosraus''  is  a  classic  masterpiece  in 
both,  hardly  equalled,  never  surpassed,  by  any 
work  on  its  theme.  It  required  a  ripe  man  in 
a  ripe  age  to  produce  it.  Fechner,  of  Leipzig, 
also  distinguished  in  the  two  departments,  oc- 
cupies a  Spinozistic-Kantian  position.  Virchow 
is  one  of  the  glories  of  the  medical  faculty  of  the 
University  of  Berlin,  iirst  President  of  the  Ger- 
man Anthropological  Association,  and  founder 
of  Cellular  Pathology. 

The  names  of  Wundt,  Czolbe,  Planck, 
Hackel,  Schleiden,  Carus,  Snell,  Vierordt, 
Tyndall,  Barnard  (of  Columbia  College,  New 
York),  Bronn,  Kolliker,  Nagele  are  also 
among  those  cited  in  the  controversy.  The 
array  is  an  imposing  one,  and  its  main  weight 
is  thrown  against  Materialism,  and  with  increas- 
ing unity  and  force.  Science  is  already  fulfill- 
ing the  grand  duty  v/hich  Scholten  says  is  im- 
posed on  her,  the  duty  of  repelling  the  assertion 
that  "science  is  materialistic.'^  ''No  possible 
"  explanation,"  says  Barnard,  '•  of  mental  phe- 


54  INTRODUCTION. 

"  nomena  can  be  founded  upon  a  hypothesis 
"  which  attempts  to  identify  them  with  physi- 
"  cal  forces. .  .  .  The  organic  world  furnishes  just 
"  as  conclusive  evidence  of  the  existence  of  an 
"  influence  superior  to  force,  as  the  physical 
''  world  exhibits  of  the  existence  of  force  itself. 
"  ...  As  physicists,  we  have  nothing  to  do  with 
"  mental  philosophy.  In  endeavoring  to  reduce 
''  the  phenomena  of  mind  under  the  laws  of 
"  matter  we  wander  beyond  our  depth,  we  es- 
''  tablish  nothing  certain,  we  bring  ridicule 
"  upon  the  name  of  positive  science,  and  achieve 
"but  a  single  undeniable  result,  that  of  unset- 
"tling  in  the  minds  of  multitudes,  convictions 
"  which  form  the  basis  of  their  chief  happiness. 
'' .  .  .  There  is  certainly  a  field  which  it  is  not 
"  the  province  of  physical  science  to  explore, 
"and  which,  if  we  are  wise,  we  shall  carefully 
"  refrain  from  invading." 

"  I  am  no  materialist,"  says  Huxley,  "  but, 
"  on  the   contrary,  believe  Materialism   to   in- 

"  volve  grave  philosophical  error In  so  far  as 

"  my  study  of  what  specially  characterizes  the 
"  Positive  Philosophy  has  led  me,  I  find  therein 
"little  or  nothing  of  any  scientific  value,  and  a 
''great  deal  which  is  as  thoroughly  antagonistic 
"  to  the  very  essence  of  science  as  anything  in 
"  ultramontane  Catholicism. . . .  The  further  sci- 


THE   GREAT   PHYSICISTS.  55 

"  ence  advances,  the  more  extensively  and  con- 
'' sistently  will  all  the  phenomena  of  nature  be 
"  represented  by  materialistic  formu]£e  and  sym- 
"bols.  But  the  man  of  science  who,  forgetting 
"  the  limits  of  philosophical  inquiry,  slides  from 
"these  formulae  and  symbols  into  w^jat  is  com- 
"  monly  understood  by  Materialism,  seems  to 
''  me  to  place  himself  on  a  level  with  the  mathe- 
"  matician  who  should  mistake  the  x's  and  y^s, 
"  with  which  he  works  his  problems,  for  real 
"entities,  and  with  this  further  disadvantage, 
"  as  compared  w^ith  the  mathematician,  that  the 
"blunders  of  the  latter  are  of  no  practical  con- 
"  sequence,  w^iile  the  errors  of  systematic  Ma- 
"  terialism  may  paralyze  the  energies  and  de- 
"  stroy  the  beauty  of  a  life.'' 

"  The  passage  from  the  physics  of  the  brain 
"to  the  corresponding  facts  of  consciousness," 
says  Tyndall,  "is  unthinkable.  ...  On  both 
"sides  of  the  zone  here  assigned  to  the  materi- 
"alist  he  is  equally  helpless.  .  .  .  When  we 
"  endeavor  to  pass  .  .  .  from  the  phenomena 
"  of  physics  to  those  of  thought,  we  meet  a 
"  problem  w^iich  transcends  any  conceivable 
"  expansion  of  the  powers  w^hich  we  now  pos- 
"  sess.  We  may  think  over  the  subject  again 
"and  again,  but  it  eludes  all  intellectual  pre- 
"sentation.     We  stand  at  length  face  to  face 


56  INTRODUCTION. 

"  with  the  Incomprehensible.  The  territory  of 
''  physics  is  wide,  but  it  has  its  limits,  from 
'^  which  we  look  with  vacant  gaze  into  the  re- 
*'  gion  beyond.  .  .  Having  exhausted  physics,  and 
"  reached  its  very  rim,  the  real  mystery  still 
"  looms  beyond  us.  We  have,  in  fact,  made 
^^  no  step  toward  its  solution.  And  thus  will 
"  it  ever  loom,  ever  beyond  the  bound  of  knowl- 
"  edge." 

From  these  utterances,  which  are  parallel 
wath  those  given  by  Ulrioi,  from  Bonders,  and 
Du  Bois-Reymond,  and  which  could  be  multi- 
plied indefinitely,  it  is  very  clear  that  gross  in- 
justice may  be  done  to  men  of  science,  by  con- 
founding their  Materialism  and  Non-theism,  in 
(he  sphere  of  physical  science^  with  a  total  Mate- 
rialism and  Atheism  in  a  different  sphere.  For 
the  physicist,  as  such,  is  occupied  wholly  with 
the  question.  What  does  physics  prove?  and 
not  at  all  with  the  question.  What  do  other 
sources  of  knowledge  prove  ?  He  knows  that 
unproven  is  not  disproven,  and  that  unproven 
by  one  still  less  means  disproven  by  all.  That 
sort  of  folly  is  for  the  blatant  novice  who  would 
rather  talk  "  big,"  than  talk  wisely.  The  Mate- 
rialist in  matter  is  not  of  necessity  a  Materialist 
in  mind,  and  a  non-theist  in  the  law  may  be  a 
hearty  theist  before  the  law.     Physical  science, 


THE   GREAT   PHYSICISTS.  57 

can  as  such,  be  neither  theistic  nor  atheistic,  for 
physical  science  is  totally  occupied  with  second 
causes,  and  theism  and  atheism  are  alike  occu- 
pied with  the  question  of  final  cause.  That  is 
a  question  not  of  physics  but  of  metaphysics. 
Physics  can  accumulate  the  rich  stores  of  mate- 
rial,  to  which  both  theist  and  atheist  may  resort, 
but  in  its  exclusive  sphere  it  is  neither  to  be 
lauded  for  the  uses  made  of  them  bv  the  one, 
nor  condemned  for  the  abuses  of  them  made  by 
the  other.  A  l^atural  Theology  now  could  be 
made  grander  than  any  that  has  ever  been 
written.  If  the  scientist  claims  the  common 
right  to  use  the  materials  of  physics  for  specu- 
lative purposes,  we  have  to  grant  it.  If  in 
doing  it,  he  shows  that  while  in  the  sphere  of 
physics  he  may  be  strong,  in  that  of  metaphys- 
ics he  is  weak,  we  must  not  condemn  him  as  the 
strong  physicist  but  as  the  weak  metaphysician. 
It  is  not  science  but  the  want  of  science  which 
is  at  fault.  When  physical  science,  the  science 
of  phenomena  and  of  second  causes,  not  of  es- 
sence and  ultimate  cause,  reaches  any  point,  at 
which  the  next  step  involves  either  affirmation 
or  denial  of  a  Supreme  Cause,  it  has  reached 
its  Rubicon.  Every  step  after  that  is  in  defiance 
of  its  own  commission,  an  assumption  of  author- 
ity that  does  not  belong  to  it.     It  is  Imperator 


58  INTRODUCTION. 

on  its  own  side,  it  is  Usurper  on  the  other. 
Physical  science  nia^^  give  us  Chemistries,  Geol- 
ogies, Treatises  on  Mechanics,  but  it  has  no 
right  to  give  us  manuals  of  Ethics,  or  systems  of 
Philosophy  or  of  Theology,  though  the  writers 
of  manuals  and  systems  may  find  rich  sugges- 
tions in  it  for  both. 

Much  is  said  in  these  reviews  of  the  mis- 
chievous spirit  and  tendency  of  Strauss's  book 
in  various  aspects,  social,  political,  and  relig- 
ious. "We  had  not  reckoned  it  possible,"  says 
Rauwenhoff,  "  that  David  Priedrich  Strauss 
^'  should  ofier  himself  as  the  mouthpiece  of  a 
"  reactionary  conservatism  like  that  of  Prussia. 
"It  is  a  new  illustration  of  the  way  in  which 
"  Skepticism  invariably  ends  in  bringing  grist 
"to  the  mill  of  Absolutism.  .  .  .  Strauss  comes 
"  involuntarily  to  the  deification  of  the  strong 
"  arm.  Ilis  tranquillity  in  view  of  the  future  of 
"  the  German  race,  rests  on  his  trust  in  the  rail- 
"  itary  despotism  of  Prussia.  Goethe  and  Hum- 
"  BOLDT,  the  heroes  of  culture  and  advance,  are 
"  dead,  but,  thank  Heaven,  w^e  have  in  their 
"  place  Bismarck  and  Moltkb,  the  heroes  of 
"diplomacy  and  war!  .  .  .  This  is  a  time  to 
"  press  the  claim  of  freedom  over  against  that 
"of  statutory  regulation,  the  claim  of  right 
"  over  against  might,  of  culture  over  against  mil- 


MISCHIEVOUS   TENDENCIES.  59 


cc 


itary  despotism.  And  at  this  crisis  comes  this 
"  son  of  Swabia,this  independent  man  of  science, 
"  this  standard-bearer  of  free  thinking — comes 
"with  a  new  programme  for  state  and  society, 
"  and  in  this  programme  he  speaks  for  sound 
''  popular  improvement,  for  freedom  of  the 
"press,  for  elementary  and  higher  education, 
"  for  the  moral  exaltation  of  the  spirit  of  the 
"people — not  a  solitary  word;  but  in  place  of 
"  all  these  we  have  a  commendation  of  the  old 
"  state-policy,  under  the  broad  shield  of  Bis- 
^'MARCK,  with  the  sword  of  the  Empire  in  his 
"  hand,  and  in  the  background,  as  the  head- 
"  stone  of  this  edifice  of  state,  the  scaffold.  .  .  . 
"  What  good  might  he  have  wrought  had  he 
"  employed  his  power  as  a  writer  to  cast  into 
"  the  wakened  national  feeling  seeds  of  the 
"spirit  of  freedom,  of  humanity,  of  civic  virtue, 
"  of  progress  in  trade  and  the  industrial  pur- 
"  suits,  in  science  and  art ;  had  he  said  to  his 
"people  that  as  they  had  once  more  risen  to 
"the  first  rank  among  European  powers  they 
"had  new  duties  to  fulfil,  that  Germany  was  to 
"  show  to  the  world  how  a  great  people  can  wed 
"Freedom  to  Order,  can  become  the  bulwark 
"  of  the  Right,  and  go  forth  upon  the  pathway 
"  of  a  true  progress.  He  might  have  taught 
"  them  this.     What  has  he  taught  them  ?     I  see 


60  INTRODUCTION. 

"  but  one  possible  practical  application  which 
"  Germans  can  make  of  Strauss's  book,  and 
"that  is  to  run  away  from  the  Church  as  fast  as 
"  they  can,  and  find  safety  from  all  sorts  of 
"perils  by  creeping  under  the  skirts  of  the 
"  Chancellor  of  the  Empire. 

"  Strauss  may  be  a  fine  thinker,  but  he  has  no 
"  heart  for  his  own  people.  No  !  and  more  than 
"  this,  he  has  no  heart  for  the  people  at  all.  He 
"asks,  'Is  Lessing's  "Nathan"  or  Goethe's 
"'"Hermann  and  Dorothea''  harder  to  under- 
" '  stand  or  less  replete  with  the  "  truths  of  sal- 
"  '  vation,"  or  does  it  embrace  fewer  golden  sen- 
"  '  tences  than  an  Epistle  of  Paul  or  one  of  John's 
"'Discourses  of  Christ?'  Is  this  sport  or  ear- 
"  nest?  When  the  poor  man  out  of  the  masses 
"  must  put  away  his  Bible,  and  asks  for  some- 
"  thing  from  which  he  can  draw  a  word  to  build 
"  up  his  soul,  we  are  to  put  in  his  hands  '  Nathan 
"the  Wise'  and  'Hermann  and  Dorothea.' 
"Strauss  himself  could  not  have  the  heart  to 
"  practice  what  he  recommends.  Even  he  must 
"  have  a  suspicion  at  least,  what  this  Bible,  on 
"  which  he  charges  so  many  oflences,  means  to 
"  the  simple,  pious  soul.  Understand  it !  Alas  ! 
"  spare  yourself  the  trouble  of  explaining  it  if 
"you  imagine  that  your  explanation  is  for  the 
"  first  time  to  unseal  the  springs  of  power  in  life, 


MISCHIEVOUS   TENDENCIES.  61 

"and  of  courage  in  death,  which  this  old  Scrip- 
"  ture  word  has  for  the  pious  poor.  You  feel 
"  an  intellectual  pride  in  deciphering  the  num- 
"  ber  of  the  Beast  in  the  Apocalypse ;  but  think 
"you  that  the  simple  Bible-reader  has  been 
"  waiting  for  your  discovery,  to  dispel  the  ter- 
"  rors  of  death,  in  the  light  of  that  heavenly  Je- 
"rusalem,  where  God  himself  shall  wipe  away 
"  all  tears  from  his  eyes  ?  You  may  explain  the 
"  train  of  the  connection  in  the  Epistle  to  the 
"  Romans  better  than  Luther  could,  but  with 
"  the  words  '  the  righteous  shall  live  by  his 
"faith,'  Luther  broke  from  the  neck  of  his 
"  native  land  the  yoke  of  superstition.  You 
"speak  of  the  classics?  Here,  too,  we  have 
"  classics,  these  old  Psalmists  of  Israel,  whose 
"  sacred  poetrj^,  though  two  thousand  years 
"  have  past,  wakens  the  tenderest  chords  of  the 
"  human  heart.  And  Jesus — Jesus,  whom  you 
"  call  a  visionary,  a  laggard  in  the  development 
"  of  mind — is  he  who  spake  the  words,  every 
"  one  of  which  is  felt  in  the  incalculable  sum 
"of  blessings  imparted  to  our  race  in  all  its 
"struggles  and  sorrows.  . .  The  people  is  indeed 
"  uncultivated,  but  in  some  things  it  has  sound 
"  feeling,  and  it  would  rise  in  wrath  at  the  at- 
"  tempt  to  substitute,  on  the  wall  of  the  poor 
"  cottage  room,  the  head  of  Goethe  for  the  Head 


62  INTRODUCTION. 

"  crowned  with  thorns,  or  to  put  the  three  well 
'' selected,  well  arranged  quartettes  in  place  of 
''  the  old  hymns  in  the  Church,  sung  to  the  sol- 
"  emn  cadence  of  the  organ.  To  attempt  it 
"  would  bring  proof  that  it  is  one  thing  to  play 
''  the  trifler  with  the  old  faith,  and  another  and 
"  a  wholly  different  one  to  dislodge  it  from  the 
"  hearts  and  lives  of  the  people. 

"Had  Strauss  seen  much  of  the  life  of  the 
"  people,  it  is  impossible  that  there  should  have 
"  been  no  note  of  sadness  at  the  close  of  his 
"  book,  in  the  contemplation  of  the  loss  involved 
"  to  mankind,  were  his  faith  really  to  supplant 
"  the  old  faith.  He  could  not  speak  so  light- 
-heartedly of  man's  sense  of  imperfection,  .  .  of 
"  the  abandoning  of  trust  in  providence, .  .  of  the 
"  unsatisfying  in  life.  Could  I  believe  as  Strauss 
"  believes,  I  might  feel  myself  bound  to  utter 
"  my  convictions,  but  I  think  I  could  not  refrain 
''  from  tears  as  I  spoke.  I  should  weep  at  the 
''  thought  that  there  were  thousands  who  would 
"  not  merely  lose  what  I  lost,  but  who  in  this 
"  loss  would  see  everything  vanish,  all  that 
"  touched  their  life  with  a  brighter  hue,  all  that 
"  imparted  to  its  sordidness  something  of  poetry, 
"  to  its  sadness  something  of  consolation. 

"No   man    can   see  unmoved,  the  cynicism 
"  which  tears  away  from  a  child  its  ideal — and 


THE   POLITICAL   ELEMENTS   IN  STRAUSS.       63 

"  Strauss  !  the  people  for  wliorn  thou  hast  no 
"  more  than  this  cynic  comfort,  this  people  is 
"  but  a  child,  a  child  of  poverty  and  sorrow." 

HuBER  quotes  the  saying  of  Mazzini  that 
''the  doctrine  of  Materialism  is  the  philosophy 
"  of  all  epochs  which  are  withering  to  the  grave, 
"and  of  all  nations  sinking  to  extinction." 
"  We  dare  not  allow,"  says  Ruber,  at  the  close 
of  his  book,  '•  the  spirit  of  the  idealistic  philos- 
"  ophy  to  be  lost,  if  we  are  to  have  any  guaran- 
"  tee  of  a  great  and  happy  future  for  our  native 
"land." 


THE  POLITICAL  ELEMENTS  EST  STRAUSS. 

Strauss  has  had  an  extraordinary  felicity  in 
disgusting  men  of  both  the  great  political  ten- 
dencies. The  Conservatives  are  disgusted  with 
his  destructivism  of  principles,  and  the  Progres- 
sives with  his  heartless  sj'cophancy  to  the  ruling 
powers,  in  practice.  He  lays  the  foundation  of 
a  Red  Republic,  and  builds  upon  it  a  structure 
of  absolute  Despotism.  Neither  party  is  satis- 
fied with  either  part.  The  Red  Republicans 
abhor  the  foundation,  for  it  is  made  the  founda- 
tion for  monarchy.  The  Monarchists  abhor  the 
structure,  for  it  is  made  to  rest  on  the  quick- 
sands  of  the   most  ultra  infidelity,  which  they 


64  INTRODUCTION. 

know  demoralizes  the  people,  and  gives  terrible 
power  to  the  dangerous  classes.  Each  class 
abhors  the  thing  they  would,  because  it  is  bound 
up  with  the  thing  they  would  not. 

H.  Lang,  "  the  radical  of  radicals,  and  one  of 
Strauss's  most  fervent  admirers,"  expresses  the 
disappointment  he  had  experienced  in  reading 
his  last  book.  "Rarely,"  says  he,  "have  my 
"  anticipations  proved  so  empty,  as  on  the  read- 
ying of  this  book.  To  be  sure  it  contains  not 
''  a  few  things  which  are  suggestive  and  beau- 
"tifully  put,  but  as  a  whole  it  disgusted  me; 
"  it  was  pervaded  by  such  an  air  of  senility, 
"an  aristocratic  daintiness,  thrusting  out  of 
"  sight  the  real  forces  of  life,  a  sort  of  dis- 
"  agreeable  sourness  and  crabbedness,  when  I 
"looked  for  that  repose  of  unprejudiced  esti- 
"  mate,  which  is  the  token  of  a  wise  man." 

"  Our  author,"  says  Rauweniioff,  "  is  a 
"  criminalist  of  the  old  style.  He  laughs  at  all 
"  the  twaddle  about  humanity  and  the  rights  of 
"  men.  He  huzzaed  for  the  laws  against  tlie 
"Jesuits;  he  went  in  for  a  summary  taking  of 
"  the  people  of  the  International  over  the 
"  border,  and  he  sighs  at  the  thought  how  many 
"are  likely  to  give  the  gallows  the  slip." 

"  It  is  worthy  of  note,"  says  Miciielis,  "  how 
"  anxiousl^^  Strauss  regards  the  probability  of 


REACTIONARY  TENDENCY  OF  STRAUSS's  BOOK.     65 


"ail  outbreak  of  savagery  in  the  world  of  the 
"  new  faith,  and  how  desirous  he  is  to  restore  or 
"  preserve  all  the  means  of  coercive  restraint. 
"  The  death-penalty  is  to  be  retained  and  made 
"  more  general  (though  Strauss  nowhere  has  a 
"place  for  the  element  of  expiation  for  guilt). 
"  The  right  of  voting  is  to  be  restricted,  the 
"  right  of  mutual  association  on  the  part  of 
"  workingmen  is  to  be  abrogated.  lie  is  a 
"  friend  of  nobility,  monarchy,  war,  and,  as  a 
"  matter  of  course,  standing  armies.  What  in- 
"  fatuation  !  As  if  everything  of  that  sort  would 
"  not  bend  like  willow-twigs,  or  be  torn  up  by 
"the  roots,  like  pines,  when  the  hurricane 
"breaks  loose,  which  is  sure  to  come,  if  the 
"people  should  ever  reach  Strauss's  convic- 
"  tions,  and  act  them  out  in  earnest.'' 


THE  REACTIONARY   TENDENCY  OF   STRAUSS'S  BOOK. 

Of  the  tendency  of  the  book  by  reaction^  the 
general  opinion  of  the  reviewers  is  that  ex- 
pressed by  Sporri  :  "  Anxious  souls,  when  they 
"  see  themselves  reduced  to  the  alternative  of 
"  choosing  between  the  Church-faith  intact,  and 
"  the  results  here  oftered,  may  be  seized  with 
"  terror  at  all  criticism,  and  throw  themselves 
"  into  the  arms  of  orthodoxy ;  or,  taking  warn- 


66  INTRODUCTION. 

"  ing  from  Strauss,  that  they  cannot  stand  fast 
"  by  the  Protestant  orthodoxy,  nor  even  by  that 
"  of  the  Old  Catholics,  may  find  themselves 
"  guided  in  the  straight  path  to  Rome.  Of  those 
"  who  have  been  standing  in  an  attitude  of  indif- 
'^  ference  to  the  Church  and  to  Christianity,  and 
"  who  will  clap  their  hands,  there  is  a  large  class 
"  with  whom  it  will  not  be  pleasant  for  Strauss 
"  to  be  associated.  Others,  thoughtful  of  the 
'*•  welfare  of  the  people,  will  continue  to  com- 
"  mend  othodox}^  as  the  only  proper  diet  for 
"  the  masses,  with  the  understanding,  however, 
''  that  they  are  not  to  be  expected  to  partake  of 
"  this  nutriment  themselves."  "  On  many  a 
"  reader,  however,  this  book  may  have  an  effect 
"  like  that  which  the  philosophy  of  Schopen- 
"  HAUER  had  on  Strauss.  It  may  produce  in 
"  such  a  reader  a  reaction  against  this  whole 
"  method  of  treating  the  Christian  religion,  and 
"  may  recall  to  him  the  secret  threads  which 
"  still  bind  him  to  Christianity." 

Of  the  provision  for  an  effectual  antidote  to 
Strauss's  book,  Rauwexhoff  says,  at  the  end 
of  his  discussion  :  "  Strauss's  style  of  thinking 
"  is  a  power  which-is  not  to  be  vanquished  by 
"  anathemas,  or  by  critical  processes.  The  sole 
"  power  before  which  it  must  give  way  is  the 
^'  power  of  a  religion,  which,  without  impairing 


ULEIcfs   REVIEW   OF   STEAUSS.  67 

"  in  any  respect  the  just  claims  of  science,  and 
"  without  bringing  any  derangement  into  the 
'>  natural  unfolding  of  social  life,  shall  permeate 
"  every  part  of  our  human  existence  with  its 
"  sanctifying  and  quickening  might." 

TJLRICI'S  REVIEW  OF  STRAUSS. 

Distinguished  among  the  numerous  reviews 
of  Strauss  is  the  Criticism  contributed  by  Ul- 
Rici  to  the  "Zeitschrift  fiir  Philosophic  und 
Philosophische  Kritik.'' 

Dr.  Hermann  Ulrici  (born  1806),  Professor 
of  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Halle,  is 
known  to  English  readers  by  the  translation  of 
his  work  on  the  Dramatic  Art  of  Shakspeare, 
London,  1846.  He  has  written  other  works  on 
Literary  History  and  Criticism ;  but  the  great 
strength  of  his  life  has  been  put  into  works  of 
which  the  English  public  knows  little,  but  of 
which  it  would  be  a  great  gain  to  it  to  know 
much.  To  all  students  of  the  best  philosophical 
writings  of  living  German  authors,  Ulrici  is 
known  as  the  author  of  a  number  of  works 
which  show  a  rare  mastery  of  the  physical  and 
metaphysical  sciences;  works  which  are  models 
of  logical  thinking  and  of  noble  style.  He  is 
not  an  ambitious  novice,  pulling  himself  into 


68  INTRODUCTION. 

notice  by  dragging  at  the  skirts  of  a  celebrity 
of  the  hour;  but  is  a  man  who,  in  the  best 
elements  of  true  renown,  is  Strauss's  superior. 
Ulrici  is  not  a  theologian,  and  does  not  write 
from  a  theological  point  of  view.  For  the  im- 
mediate moral  force  and  efiectiveness  of  the 
review  we  translate,  this  is  an  advantage.  It 
anticipates  the  very  pitiful  but  very  common 
pretence,  by  which  the  school  of  loose  thinkers 
conveniently  sets  aside  a  work  from  the  hand  of 
one  whose  life  business  it  is  to  defend  the  great 
principles  of  a  pure  Theism.  They  solve  his 
defence  by  insisting  that  he  makes  it  only  be- 
cause it  is  his  business.  The  very  men  who 
under  the  pretence  of  physical  theory,  are  little 
more  than  uncalled  dabblers  in  theology,  of 
whose  primary  principles  they  show  themselves 
too  ignorant  even  to  misrepresent  them  effec- 
tively, make  an  outcry  against  the  theologian 
as  an  intruder  into  other  men's  province — their 
province — when,  however  modestly  and  ably,  he 
defends  revealed  truth  against  pseudo-scientilic 
assumption.  In  Ulrici  we  have  a  great  phil- 
osophical thinker,  deciding  by  the  processes  of 
a  sober,  logical  philosophy  the  claim  which 
Strauss  was  most  ambitious  to  establish  for 
himself,  the  claim  to  be  a  rational  thinker.  It 
is  a  claim  with  the  fall  of  which  his  book  falls. 


ULEICl's   REVIEW   OF   STRAUSS.  69 

The  confutation  of  Strauss's  philosophy  is  the 
conipletest  confutation  of  what  is  most  impor- 
tant in  his  "  new  faith/'  If  in  this  he  is  not  a 
philosophical  thinker,  he  is  nothing.  In  the 
album  of  the  Crown  Princess  of  Prussia,  the 
year  before  his  death  (he  died  February  9th, 
1874),  Strauss  wrote :  "  Though  the  wise  and 
"  honored  refuse  me  a  place  among  them,  I 
"  shall  not  complain,  if  I  be  but  reckoned  with 
"  the  rational  Whatever  be  the  place  of 
Strauss  in  the  judgment  of  after  generations, 
it  will  surely  not  be  with  "  the  rational,''  if  the 
rational  are  those  who  have  used  the  highest 
reason  in  the  service  of  the  purest  truth. 

Ulrici's  review  shows  his  characteristic  abil- 
ity. It  is  a  masterpiece  of  logic,  fact,  and 
practical  force.  It  is  clear  and  cogent,  compact 
yet  comprehensive.  Letting  Strauss  speak  for 
himself,  both  in  statement  and  argument,  it 
meets  him  calmly  and  answers  him  overwhelm- 
ingly. Strauss  is  fond  of  the  weapons  of  ridi- 
cule, but  he  is  no  master  in  the  use  of  them, 
but  he  provokes  sarcasm  in  reply,  less  by  his 
feeble,  and  sometimes  coarse  wit,  than  by  his 
ineffable,  self-satisfied  absurdity.  In  his  worst 
displays  of  this  sort  he  cannot  be  burlesqued,  he 
can  only  be  exhibited.     Ulrici's  review  never 

3 


70  INTRODUCTION. 

makes  Strauss  ridiculous^;  that  it  shows  him  so, 
is  Strauss's  own  fault. 

Every  one  desires  to  know  what  Strauss  held 
and  why  he  held  it,  but  very  many  have  not  the 
time  or  the  inclination  to  read  his  book.  Every 
one  should  wish  to  know  how  Strauss  is  over- 
thrown on  the  very  ground  he  has  selected  for 
his  battle.  Few,  however,  have  access  to  the 
ampler  works  which  have  been  written  in  reply 
to  him,  and  few  would  have  time  or  desire  to 
read  them,  if  they  had.  As  warfare  grows 
older,  battles  become  shorter.  In  modern  tac- 
tics the  demonstrated  ability  to  do  a  thing  often 
makes  it  unnecessary  to  do  it.  To  pierce  the 
centre  makes  the  beating  of  the  wings  a  mere 
matter  of  detail,  and  in  Ulrici's  review  Strauss's 
centre  is  annihilated.  His  wings  are  not  worth 
saving,  and  not  worth  beating. 

This  volume,  then,  is  enough  for  its  end.  It 
is  a  discussion,  scientific,  yet  perfectly  intelli- 
gible to  every  educated  reader,  of  all  the  most 
vital  of  the  speculative  questions  of  the  day. 
It  furnishes  one  of  the  best  antidotes  to  the 
widely  circulated  and  dangerous  book  of 
Strauss,  the  weaknesses  and  internal  contradic- 
tions of  which  it  lays  bare.  To  the  general 
reader,  as  well  as  to  the  man  of  science,  to  all 
who  are  in  the  perils  or  doubts  of  Materialism, 


ULRICI'S   REVIEW   OF   STRAUSS.  71 

Ulrici's  "  Eeview  of  Strauss,"  rich  in  matter 
and  classic  in  execution,  yet  small  in  bulk,  will 
be  invaluable.  It  shows  how  necessary  and  great 
a  part  is  borne  by  true  philosophical  thinking 
in  the  confutation  of  the  false.  If  Germany 
gives  to  the  world  the  ablest  presentations  of 
the  wrong,  she  also  furnishes  the  noblest  vindi- 
cations of  the  right. 

FiCHTE  says  of  Ulrici's  review,  "  With  such 
"  keenness  of  logic,  such  inexorable  sequence  of 
"  conclusion,  has  it  laid  bare  the  internal  con- 
"  tradictions,  the  hastiness  of  inference,  the  un- 
"  sustained  assumption,  which  reveal  themselves 
"in  the  particular  parts  as  well  as  in  the  gen- 
"  eral  position  of  Strauss's  book,  as  to  place  be- 
"  yond  all  doubt  the  final  judgment  in  regard  to 
^' its  philosophical  vsiiue.'^  Nippold  says:  ''To 
"  consider  it  necessary  to  say  a  single  word  in 
''regard  to  Ulrici's  significance  in  the  devel- 
"  opment  of  the  modern  philosophy,  would  be 
"  as  absurd  as  the  attempt  to  ignore  a  Lotze  or 
"  a  Trendlenburg.  His  judgment  on  Strauss, 
"  as  a  philosophical  thinker,  cuts  with  an  al- 
"  most  unsurpassable  acuteness."  "  Any  one 
"who  will  recall,"  says  another  German  re- 
viewer, "  the  haughty  self-sufficiency  with  which 
"  Strauss  has  been  making  his  appeal  to  '  phi- 
"losoph}^,'   meaning  the  Hegelian,  as  if  there 


72  INTRODUCTION. 

''  were  no  other,  and  pleasing  himself  with  the 
"idea  of  being  a  philosopher,  will  readily  iin- 
"  derstand,  why  among  all  the  writings  in  oppo- 
''  sition  to  his  book,  that  of  Ulrici  must  most 
"  deeply  cut  to  the  quick  his  gigantic  vanity/' 

In  the  translation,  Ulrici's  notes  have  been 
incorporated  into  the  text,  but  are  distinguished 
by  square  brackets.  The  various  subdivisions 
of  his  discussion  have  been  numbered  and  fur- 
nished with  headings.  All  his  citations  of 
Strauss  have  been  carefully  verified.  Where 
Strauss  has  made  a  change  in  the  later  edi- 
tions, the  change  is  noted,  and  the  paging  of 
the  sixth  edition  is  added  to  that  of  the  edi- 
tion used  by  Ulrici.  The  Introduction  has 
been  designed  to  give  a  general  view  of  the 
Materialism  of  our  da}^,  and  a  special  presenta- 
tion of  the  most  important  points  in  the  contro- 
versy raised  by  the  book  of  Strauss.  Many  of 
the  strongest  and  most  brilliant  things  which 
have  been  called  forth  in  the  reviews  of  Strauss 
are  brought  together,  and,  w^ithlJLRici's  critique, 
will  help  to  make  the  volume  an  epitome  of  the 
great  points  in  discussion.  It  will  aid  the 
reader  who  desires  to  be  brought  fully  abreast 
with  the  results  and  questions  of  the  latest  in- 
vestigation and  speculation  of  our  day. 


ULRICrS  REVIEW  OF  STRAUSS: 

''THE  OLD  FAITH  AND  THE  NEW  EAITH." 


L 

STRAUSS  CONSIDERED  AS  A  PHILOSOPHICAL  THENTKER. 

David  Friedrich  Strauss  is  a  celebrity.  All 
bis  works  bave  run  tbrougb  so  and  so  many 
editions.  Tbe  most  important  of  tbem  belong 
to  tbe  department  of  Tbeology,  or,  to  speak 
more  accurately,  to  tbe  department  of  tbe  Pbil- 
osopby  of  Religion.  It  is  a  matter  of  interest, 
tberefore,  even  to  tbe  pbilosopber  by  profession, 
wben  a  man  like  Strauss  comes  fortb  in  tbe 
evening  of  bis  life  witb  a  confession  of  bis  faitb. 
Our  interest,  bowever,  in  tbis  direction  is,  as 
a  matter  of  course,  confined  to  tbe  question, 
Wbat  are  tbe  pbilosopbical  grounds — wbat  is 
tbe  pbilosopbical  tenableness  of  tbis  new  faitb? 
Tbe  question  wbetber  Strauss  is  rigbt  or  wrong, 
or  bow  far  be  may  be  rigbt  or  wrong,  in  bis  way 
of  apprebending  tbe  origin,  development,  signifi- 
cance, trutb  or  untrutb  of  bistorical  Cbristianity, 


74       STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

and  of  the  doctrines  of  the  Church,  is  a  question 
of  a  purely  theological  character,  with  which  we 
have  here  nothing  to  do.  We  are  interested  solely 
in  Strauss  as  a  "philosophical  thinker.  We  have 
read  his  book,  simply  because  we  felt  warranted 
in  the  assumption,  that  a  philosopher  who  had 
reached  the  distinguished  position  held  by 
Strauss  among  scientific  writers,  would  mean 
by  the  faith  to  which  he  gives  his  adherence 
something  more  than  his  mere  individual  faith,  his 
subjective  view  or  conviction.  Such  a  faith  could 
inspire  very  little  interest  in  our  mind.  We 
assumed  that  this  new  faith  would  be  offered 
and  argued,  philosophicallj^,  as  a  form  and  appre- 
hension of  religion  objectively  justified.  In  this 
expectation  we  have  been  grievously  disappoint- 
ed. We  find,  on  the  contrary,  that  the  "new 
faith'^  is  utterly  destitute  of  any  philosophical 
foundation.  In  fact  we  are  forced  to  the  con- 
viction, that  the  book  before  us  very  closely  re- 
sembles a  philosophical  bankrupt's  statement  on 
the  part  of  its  renowned  author. 

This  conviction  of  ours,  which  to  the  mass  of 
the  admirers  of  Strauss  and  of  the  disciples  of 
the  new  faith,  may  seem  supremely  paradoxical, 
and  supremely  heretical,  we  have  made  it  our 
task  thoroughly  to  vindicate,  and  we  are  not 
without  hope  of  being  able  to  do  it. 


"the  new  faith  and  the  old  faith/^    75 

We  lay  down  as  a  rule  or  criterion  the  prin- 
ciple, that  a  philosopher,  who  on  essential  points 
not  only  puts  forth  as  established  truths  asser- 
tions which  are  completely  without  evidence, 
and  wholly  untenable,  but  contradicts  himself 
again  and  again,  has  no  claim  to  be  called  a 
philosopher.  The  validity  of  the  principle  will 
be  granted  by  every  philosopher,  and,  it  is  to  be 
hoped,  by  all  who  claim  to  be  a  part  of  what  is 
called  the  cultivated  class. 


II. 

what  STRAUSS  PROPOSES  IN  "THE  NEW  FAITH  AND 
THE  OLD  faith:"  HIS  REAL  AIM  THE  DESTRUC- 
TION OF  THE  OLD  FAITH. 

At  an  early  stage  of  the  discussion  Strauss 
explains  what  he  means,  and  what  he  does  not 
mean  by  the  ''  we,"  in  whose  name  he  speaks. 
"We  do  not  involve  in  our  plan  any  changes  at 
'^  all,  for  the  time,  in  the  outside  world.  We 
"  do  not  dream  of  overthrowing  any  of  the 
"churches,  for  we  know  that  to  innumerable 
"persons  a  church  is  still  a  necessity.  It  does 
"  not  seem  to  us  that  the  time  has  yet  come  even 
"for  a  new  construction — not  the  construction 
"of  a  church,  but,  after  the  church  has  crum- 
"  bled  into  final  ruin,  the  construction  of  a  new 


76       STBAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

"  organization  of  the  ideal  elements  in  the  vari- 
*'ous  forms  of  national  life.  Nor  would  we 
"  merely  patch  and  vamp  up  the  old  structures, 
"for  in  such  a  course  we  see  only  a  repression 
''  of  the  process  of  formation.  We  can  only 
"work  in  stillness,  so  that  in  the  future  some- 
"  thing  new  may  shape  itself  out  of  that  disin- 
"  tegration  of  the  old,  which  must  inevitably 
"  come."*^ 

This  means,  then,  that  Strauss  has  taken  up 
his  pen  not  for  the  new  organization  of  the  ideal 
elements  in  the  life  of  nations — for  the  time  has 
not  come  for  that — but  only  for  the  future  self- 
evolution  of  something  new,  out  of  the  inevitable 
disintegration  of  the  old.  But  this  "  new,''  if  it 
involve  faith  and  religion,  can  consist  only  in  a 
new  formation  of  the  "  ideal  elements  in  the 
forms  of  national  life,"  and  these  are  the  only 
things  on  which  it  is  possible  to  work,  if  we  are 
to  organize  them  anew.  In  the  sphere  of  the 
ideal,  organization  is  but  a  substitute,  a  more 
pregnant  word  for  formation  ;  and  not  in  the 
future,  but  in  the  present  only  can  we  work /or 
the  future.  This  is  a  problem  then  for  whose 
solution  the  time  has  not  come,  for  whose  solu- 
tion, therefore,  it   is   impossible   to    work,    and 

*  Der  Alt.  u.  Neu.  Glaub.  Sechst.  Aufl.  1873,  p.  8. 


^^THE   NEW   FAITH   AND   THE   OLD   FAITH/^      77 

this  is  the  solution  on  which  Strauss  goes  to 
work.  This  work  he  proposes  to  do  "in  still- 
ness;^^ and  to  accomplish  this  end,  he  publishes 
books,  which  he  no  doubt  expects  and  wishes 
may  find  a  hearty  response. 

The  "new,''  which  he  has  in  his  eye,  is  some- 
thing which  is  to  form  "  itself  of  itself ^^^  but  he  is 
going  to  "  work''  so  that  it  may  form  itself.  He 
proposes  then  to  work  for  something  which  has 
no  need  of  his  co-working,  and  which  can  be  ad- 
vantaged by  his  work,  either  not  at  all,  or  only 
so  far  as  his  work  prepares  the  ground  by  reliev- 
ing it  of  rubbish  and  levelling  it — in  a  word,  by 
a  complete  removal  of  the  old.  But  this,  it 
seems,  is  not  the  purpose  of  his  work,  for  he 
"  does  not  dream  of  overthrowing  any  of  the 
churches."  But  as  in  this  declaratory  act  one 
statement  is  all  the  time  contradicting  another, 
we  are,  at  the  very  outstart,  left  standing  in 
hopeless  perplexity  before  the  question :  What 
is  Strauss  really  aiming  at  ?  What  was  his  pre- 
cise object  in  writing  and  publishing  his  book? 

In  the  course  of  his  discussion,  indeed,  we 
are  not  long  left  in  ignorance  as  to  what  he  pur- 
poses, and  as  to  what  he  is  doing.  It  is  very 
speedily  apparent,  in  spite  of  his  protestation  to 
the  contrary,  that  he  has  no  definite  aim  beyond 
the  destruction  of  the  old.     This  is  rendered 


78      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

very  clear,  in  part,  by  his  elaborate  assaults  not 
only  upon  the  orthodox  apprehension  of  Chris- 
tianity, bnt  upon  every  other,  even  the  free  or 
rationalistic  view.  It  is  clear,  also,  from  the 
fact  that  the  new,  with  which  he  would  fill  up 
the  empty  space,  and  which  he  styles  ''  The 
Modern  View  of  the  World,"  is  at  bottom  noth- 
ing new,  and  nothing  at  all  positive,  but  is  the 
pure  negation  of  faith,  as  it  is  a  downright  re- 
pudiation of  all  the  "ideal  elements"  of  our 
human  estate — it  is  nothing  more  than  naked 
atheism  and  materialism. 


III. 
''are  we  still  christians?" 

Into  that  polemic,  as  we  have  already  said,  we 
do  not  design  to  enter.  We  commit  to  theolo- 
gians the  answer  to  the  question.  What  was  the 
teaching  of  Christ,  can  we  understand  it,  and 
what  is  its  meaning?  We  pass  over,  therefore, 
the  entire  first  part  of  the  book,  bearing  the 
superscription,  "Are  we  still  Christians?"  It 
needs  no  such  discussion  to  make  it  clear  that 
this  is  a  question,  the  answer  to  which  every  one 
will  determine  at  his  own  pleasure.  Whether 
Strauss  does,  or  does  not  regard  himself  as  a 
Christian,  is  in  itself  of  no  consequence  at  all, 


"have  we  religion  still?"  79 

so  far  as  the  interests  of  Christianty  are  in- 
volved. To  be  sure,  he  declares  it  impossible 
that  a  cultivated  man  should  profess 'the  Chris- 
tian religion,  but  that  amounts  to  nothing,  so 
long  as  the  actual  existence  of  such  men  fur- 
nishes the  direct  confutation  of  the  asserted  im- 
possibility. It  does  not  follow,  therefore,  that 
because  "we''  are  no  longer  Christians,  Chris- 
tianity must  "inevitably"  go  to  the  ground. 

IV. 

"have  we  religion  still  ?" 

After  responding  in  the  negative  to  his  own 
first  question,  Strauss  goes  on  to  a  second  one: 
"Have  we  religion  still?"  He  introduces  it 
with  a  "glance  at  the  rise  and  early  develop- 
ment of  religion  in  the  human  race."  As  we 
know  nothing  historically  m  regard  to  the  "rise" 
and  ''earliest"  development  of  religion,  the 
glance  which  Strauss  casts  on  it  is  of  course 
philosophical,  and  his  opinion  on  the  matter,  to 
have  any  value  at  all,  must  be  philosophically 
(psychologically)  confirmed.  In  place,  however, 
of  any  confirmation,  and  in  place  of  all  further 
investigation,  he  decides  the  question  in  ad- 
vance in  the  sense  of  atheism.  He  asserts  that 
"Hume  is  certainly  justified  in  maintaining  that 


80      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL,   THINKER. 

"it  has  not  been  the  disinterested  impulse  to- 
"ward  the  attainment  of  knowledge  and  truth, 
"but  the  thoroughly  selfish  impulse  toward 
"well-being,  which  originally  led  men  to  re- 
"ligion,  and  that  the  disagreeable  far  more 
"than  the  pleasant  has  been  operative  as  religi- 
"ous  motive.  The  Epicurean  derivation  of  re- 
"ligion  from  fear,  has  in  it  something  indis- 
"putably  correct.  If  everything  went  as  man 
"wishes  it,  if  he  always  had  what  he  needs,  did 
"his  plans  never  miscarry,  and  were  he  not 
"schooled  by  painful  experiences,  to  look  forth 
"sadly  on  the  future,  it  is  hardly  probable  that 
"the  idea  of  a  superior  Being  (in  the  religious 
"sense)  would  ever  be  aroused  in  him.  He 
"would  have  thought,  it  must  be  as  it  is,  and 
"would  have  accepted  it  in  stolid  indifier- 
"  ence."*  Thereupon  he  gives  us  quite  a  pretty, 
almost  poetical  picture  of  the  life  of  nature  as 
it  is  led  by  men  in  their  earliest  period,  just  as 
they  spring  from  the  bosom  of  nature.  This  is 
done  to  show  us  how  under  the  influence  of 
fear,  they  come  to  personify  the  powers  of 
nature,  and  to  make  their  gods  out  of  them. 
With  this  the  question  in  its  preliminary  stage 
is  finished  up.     It  is  certainly  a  pity,  that  this 

*  Alt.  u.  Neu.  Glaub.,  p.  93,  Sechs.  Aufl.  96. 


^^HAVE   WE   RELIGION   STILL  ?'^  81 

picture,  which  is  meant  to  supply  the  place 
of  an  argument,  is  nothing  more  than  poetry, 
in  fact  is  simply  fiction.  To  this  hour  the 
child  personifies  the  inanimate  things  which  are 
around  it,  but  not  from  fear.  It  just  as  freely 
personifies  objects  which  it  associates  with 
friendliness  and  goodness,  as  those  which  seem 
to  be  enemies,  and  excite  its  fears.  Everything 
whose  eflfects  it  experiences,  it  regards  as  a 
living  being,  endowed  with  soul,  and  will,  and 
activity.  The  reason  of  this  is,  that  it  has  thus 
far  known  no  other  operation  than  a  personal 
one,  no  other  cause  than  that  activity  which 
goes  forth  from  willing  and  wishing,  and  yet, 
in  virtue  of  that  law  of  causality,  which  uncon- 
sciously and  involuntarily  controls  its  thinking, 
it  finds  itself  necessitated  to  assume  that  there 
is  a  cause  for  everything  which  happens  to  it. 
If  it  alwavs  went  with  man  as  he  wishes,  if  he 
always  had  what  he  needs,  if  no  plan  miscarried, 
in  short  if,  as  the  proverb  phrases  it,  roasted 
pigeons  flew  into  his  mouth,  it  is  quite  possible 
that  he  would  accept  the  situation  ''with  stolid 
indifterence,"  like  cattle  grazing  in  the  pastures. 
But  then  under  these  circumstances  he  would 
probabl}^  not  have  been  man  at  all,  would  have 
formed  no  plans,  would  have  had  no  question- 
ings   touching    the    future,    would    not    have 


82      STRAUSS  AS  A   PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

troubled  himself  about  the  nature  of  things,  the 
grounds  aijd  causes  of  events,  and  topics  of  a 
similar  sort,  but, in  "stolid  indifference,"  resign- 
ing himself  to  the  perceptions  of  the  senses,  and 
the  pleasures  of  sense,  would  have  passed  his 
days,  like  the  cattle  in  grassy  meadows.  It  is 
not  then  fear  alone  which  is  the  immediate  source 
of  religion.  With  it  is  associated  the  question 
after  the  causes  of  phenomena,  the  causes  of  the 
good  and  evil  events  in  nature.  Rising  as  it 
does  involuntarily,  having  its  spring  in  the 
very  depths  of  man's  nature,  forcing  itself  on 
him  in  the  natural  events  and  natural  conditions 
of  his  own  being,  it  is  this  question  which  makes 
man  man,  it  is  this  which  announces  him  to  be 
man,  and  this  question  is  part  of  the  immediate 
source  of  religion.  It  is  because  he  conceives  of 
the  operations,  as  operations  or  manifestations  of 
a  superior  power,  that  he  is  overwhelmed  with  a 
feeling  unknown  to  the  animal,  the  feeling  of 
dependence,  and  of  conditioned  being.  This  in- 
vests his  fears  and  hopes  with  intelligent  consci- 
ousness ;hy\i  he  reaches  the  conception  of  a  power 
reigning  beyond  him,  and  above  him,  revealing 
itself  sometimes  as  his  friend,  sometimes  as  his 
foe.  And  as  he,  like  the  child,  knows  up  to 
this  period  no  other  operation  than  that  which 
is  personal,  proceeding  from  will,  acting  in  ac- 


"have  we  eeligion  still ?^'  83 

corclance  with  aim  and  purpose,  he  personifies 
the  potencies  of  nature,  which  are  made  known 
in  their  various  activities,  and  not  alone  with 
fear  and  shrinking,  but  also  with  love  and  hope, 
regards  them  as  superior  beings.  For  it  is  an 
arbitrary,  groundless  assertion,  that  the  earliest, 
the  primal  deities  were  exclusively  gods  of  fear 
and  terror.  In  all  the  grades  of  religious  develop- 
ment, even  the  very  lowest,  we  find  that  there 
were  good  and  beneficent  deities,  as  well  as  evil 
and  inimical  ones.  In  some  instances  there  were 
none  but  good  deities,  in  no  case  were  there  evil 
ones  only.  The  mental  law  of  causalitj^,  the  no- 
tion of  cause,  the  consciousness  of  dependence  and 
limitation,  demands  not  only  the  conception  but 
the  acceptance  and  admission  of  an  ultimate 
supreme  cause,  a  cause  which  is  not  the  mere 
operation  of  another  cause.  This  conception  of 
the  conditioned  is  only  possible  when  we  dis- 
tinguish the  conditioned  from  the  conditioning, 
and  the  conditioning,  in  and  of  itself,  purely 
as  conditioning,  is  necessarily  unconditioned. 
Hence  throughout,  wherever  a  development  of 
religion  takes  place,  the  religious  consciousness 
shapes  itself  into  a  faith  in  the  existence  of  a 
supreme,  unconditioned,  absolute  cause,  which 
as  such  must  be  one  only,  must  be  self-deter- 


84      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

mining,  and  must  consequently  be  a  spiritual 
force  and  activity. 


STRATJSS'S   THEORY  OF  THE  RISE  OF  RELIGION. 

All  we  have  urged  has  often  enough  been  set 
forth  in  sharp,  logical  demonstration.  Strauss 
ignores  the  whole  of  it.  To  him  "  monothe- 
ism "  is  the  result  of  the  "  life  of  a  horde  "  shut 
up  in  itself.  It  is  in  itself  no  witness  of  a 
higher  training  of  the  religious  consciousness, 
but  just  as  the  case  may  be,  it  is  higher  or 
lower  than  the  developed  polytheism,  of  the 
Greeks  for  example.  He  clings  so  closely  to  his 
principle  of  fear,  that  he  brings  it  even  into  the 
ethical  elements  of  religion  :  "  The  further  to 
"wit  a  people  advances  in  civilization,  the  less 
"does  it  restrict  its  view  to  nature,  whether  in 
"her  terrors  or  in  her  blessings,  and  the  more 
"  does  human  life,  with  its  various  relations, 
"  come  to  be  regarded  as  a  momentous  matter. 
"And  in  the  lives  of  men,  the  larger  the  pro- 
"portion  of  insecurity  and  hazard,  the  greater 
"  the  dependence  on  circumstances,  the  more 
"unavailing  human  aid  appears,  the  more  co- 
"  gently  does  man  feel  the  need  of  assuming 

powers  in  affinity  with  his  own  being,  whom 


u 


STRAUSS'S  THEORY  OF  THE  RISE  OF  RELIGION.     85 


a 


a 


"  he  can  approach  with  his  wishes  and  petitions. 
"  At  this  point  the  moral  nature  of  man  comes 
"  in  as  a  co-operative  factor.  Man  desires  to  be 
protected  not  only  against  the  passions  of 
'  others,  but  would  have  his  own  loftier  striv- 
ing guarded  against  the  powers  of  his  own 
"sensual  nature,  for  back  of  the  demands  of 
"  his  own  conscience,  he  phxces  (by  way  of  sup- 
"  port)  a  Deity  endowed  with  the  authority  to 
"  command. ''"^  What  an  amazinsjlv  odd  crea- 
ture  man  is  to  be  sure!  For  the  sake  of  his 
sensual  well-being,  he  transforms  the  powers  of 
nature  into  deities,  who,  by  prayers,  gifts,  offer- 
ings and  things  of  the  sort,  are  led  to  favor  him 
and  to  change  their  minds,  and  then  he  fur- 
nishes these  very  same  deities  with  mandatory 
power  against  his  sensual  appetites  and  selfish 
will  !  Though  the  will,  the  arbitrary  volition  of 
the  bad  man  is  a  thoroughly  internal  act,  which 
has  no  reference  at  all  to  his  outward  natural 
life,  and  tlue  forces  of  nature  which  condition  it, 
he  involves  himself  in  this  contradiction  without 
noticing  that  it  is  a  contradiction,  and  that  in  so 
doing  he  does  nothing  more  than  impose  upon 
himself!  And  stranger  still:  in  this  illusion, 
this  offspring  of  a  terrified  imagination,  he  has 

^  Alt.  u.  N.  Glaub.  57,  Sechst.  Aufl.  100,  101. 


86      STRAUSS   AS   A    PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

such  a  firm  faith,  that  for  its  sake  he  endures 
the  sorest  sufiferings,  and  joyously  submits  to 
death  itself,  though  he  has  invented  the  whole 
thing  only  for  the  sake  of  his  bodily  earthly 
well-being  ! 

VI. 

STRAUSS'S  REPUDIATION  OF  THE  ARGUMENT  FOR  THE 
EXISTENCE  OF  GOD. 

If  faith  in  God  be  no  more  than  the  contra- 
dictory result  of  human  fear,  it  can,  of  course, 
furnish  no  proof  of  the  existence  of  God. 
Strauss  repeats  therefore  the  old  assertion, 
often  enough  refuted,  that  what  is  stjded  the 
cosmological  proof  is  false,  inasmuch  as  it  leads 
us  beyond  the  world  to  a  cause  distinct  from  it- 
From  the  fact  ''  that  every  particular  being  in 
"  the  world  has  its  ground  in  another  particular 
"  being,  which  is  again  related  in  the  same  way 
"  to  another,"  it  does  not  follow,  he  argues, 
"  that  the  totality  of  individual  things  has  its 
'Aground  in  one  being  who  is  not  in  a  similar 
"  relation,  a  being  which,  unlike  the  rest,  has 
"  not  its  ground  in  another,  but  in  itself."  That 
would  be  an  inference,  he  argues,  lacking  all 
internal  coherence,  and  destitute  of  all  conclu- 
siveness.    Rather,  "If  each  of  the  things  in  the 


STRAUSS^S   REPUDIATION,   ETC.  87 

"world  has  its  ground  in  another,  and  so  on 
"forever,  we  do  not  reach  the  conception  of  a 
"  cause  whose  operation  would  be  the  world, 
"  but  of  a  substance  whose  accidents  are  the 
"  particular  beings  in  the  world :  we  do  not 
"  reach  a  God,  but  a  universe,  resting  on  itself, 
"abiding  in  its  uniformity  amid  the  eternal 
"  shifting  of  phenomena."*  Strauss  confounds 
the  notion  of  causality  with  the  menial  law  of 
causality!  The  notion  of  causality  may  allow, 
at  least  by  the  aid  of  some  plausible  twistings 
and  turnings,  of  being  transmuted  into  the  no- 
tion of  substantiality,  and  this  is  what  Strauss 
has  done.  But  with  the  menial  law  of  causality 
this  is  simply  impossible.  When  an  operation 
takes  place — an  event,  a  process,  a  change — that 
law  compels  us  to  assume  a  cause  distinct  from  the 
eflect,  even  where  we  cannot  tell  what  the  cause 
is.  The  cause  must  be  disiinct  from  the  effect, 
otherwise  there  would  be  no  twofoldness,  there 
w^ould  not  be  cause  and  eflect,  there  would  be 
only  identity,  and  consequently  there  would  be 
no  cause.  In  virtue  of  this  mental  law,  we  can- 
not conceive  of  an  endless  series  of  causes  and 
eftects — which  is  in  itself  a  process  of  thinking 
which  is  incapable  of  being  carried  out — bat  we 


*  P.  113,  Sechst.  Aufl.  116. 


88      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

ave  forced  to  presuppose  a  cause,  which  is  not  in 
turn  the  mere  effect  of  another,  but  which  is 
pure,  ultimate,  and  consequently  unconditioned 
cause.  On  any  other  supposition  we  would 
have  effects  onli/^  and  no  causes;  but  effect  with- 
out cause  is  inconceivable.  This  purely  uncon- 
ditioned cause  is  distinguished  from  all  things 
in  the  world,  not  in  that  "it  has  its  ground  in 
itself,"  but  in  the  very  fact  that  it  is  the  cause 
of  the  world :  it  has  no  ground  and  no  cause 
whatever,  but  it  is  the  cause  of  all  beside,  it  is 
the  only  true  cause.  For  the  law  of  causality 
does  not  afBrm  that  all  that  exists  must  have 
a  cause,  but  only  that  all  that  is  effected  or  pro- 
duced, all  that  happens,  all  that  comes  into 
being,  must  have  a  cause.  Inasmuch  as  this  is 
a  universal  mental  law  it  never  occurs  to  the 
unprejudiced,  unsophisticated  understanding  to 
doubt  its  universal  validity.  It  is  only  a  sort  of 
reflection  ruled  by  a  particular  tendency,  soph- 
istic, and  tangling  itself  in  its  self-manufactured 
notions  and  assumptions,  which  makes  the  at- 
tempt to  rid  itself  of  this  law,  and  thus  plunges 
itself  deeper  and  deeper  into  contradictions  and 
absurdities.  This  is  precisely  the  case  with 
Strauss.  A  universe  "  resting  on  itself"  is  an 
absurdity,  for  the  universe  does  not  "  rest,"  and 
as  a  "  universe  "  can  have  no  basis,  neither  in 


STRAUSS^S   REPUDIATION,    ETC.  89 

something  else — for  if  there  were  something 
apart  from  it  it  would  be  no  universe — nor  in 
itself,  for  a  basis  which  bears  the  existent  nature 
in  itself,  and  is  itself  the  nature  it  bears,  is  like 
the  pig-tail  of  Baron  Munchausen,  by  which 
he  held  himself  dangling  in  the  air.  And  a 
universe  "  abiding  in  its  uniformity  amid  the 
eternal  shifting  of  phenomena  ^'  is  a  contra- 
diction in  the  adjective,  because  that  which 
changes  does  not  remain  uniform^  and  because  a 
changing  phenomenon,  which  has  not  in  it  an 
essence  which  puts  forth  the  phenomenon,  and 
changes  with  it,  is  no  phenomenon,  but  an 
empty  illusion.  This  alternation,  this  rising 
and  passing  away  of  the  phenomena,  moreover, 
must  have  a  cause,  and  the  cause  must  be  dif- 
ferent from  its  effect.  This  phenomenal  uni- 
verse therefore — the  onlj'  one  we  know — must 
have  a  cause  distinct  from  itself. 

In  a  similar  style  Strauss  conducts  his  con- 
futation of  the  teleological  proof  of  the  exist- 
ence of  God.  He  concedes  indeed  that  the  uni- 
verse, or,  as  it  is  now  the  fashion  to  call  it,  the 
substance  of  the  world,  "  manifests  itself  in  an 
"  infinite  alternation  of  phenomena  linked  to- 
"  gether  not  only  causally,  but  with  reference  to 
"  a  common  end."*    But  "  nature  herself  teaches 

*  114,  Sechst.  Aufl.  117. 


90      STRAUSS  AS  A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKEK. 

"  US  that  it  is  an  erroneous  assumption  that 
"  nothing  but  conscious  intelligence  can  produce 
''  that  which  shows  adaptation  to  an  end.''  "As 
"  in  the  case  of  animal  instinct,  for  example, 
"  something  takes  place,  which  looks  as  if  it 
"  were  done  in  accordance  with  a  conscious  aim, 
"and  yet  really  is  done  without  any  such  aim, 
"so  is  it  with  the  productions  of  nature.''* 
"  How  it  comes  that  this  illusive  appearance 
"  arises,  or  that  anything  conformable  to  an  aim 
"takes  place,  and  yet  takes  place  without  any 
"preconceived  conscious  aim,  is  a  riddle  to 
"  which  Darwin. has  given  a  brilliant  solution, 
"  and  in  so  doing  has,  to  the  mind  of  every  man 
"  of  scientific  culture,  done  away  with  all  Tele- 
"ology."  To  the  authentication  of  this  point, 
however,  Strauss  does  not  come  at  once,  but 
prepares  the  way  for  it,  by  a  critique  of  the  no- 
tion of  God,  in  the  recent  philosophy,  by  a  con- 
futation of  the  proofs  of  the  immortality  of  the 
soul,  and  by  further  discussions  in  regard  to  the 
nature  of  religion.  He  then  goes  on  to  present 
a  summary  of  the  results  of  science  with  refer- 
ence to  the  formation  of  the  world,  and  the 
origin  of  life  on  our  globe.  We  propose  to  fol- 
low him  in  this  direction,  to  give  his  argument 

*  Sechst.  Aufl.  118. 


IMMORTALITY   OF   THE   SOUL.  91 

all  the  force  he  may  claim  for  it.  We  shall  pass 
by  the  critical  portions  only,  regarding  it  as  a 
matter  of  supererogation  to  subject  to  review 
this  criticism  of  his,  the  superficiality  of  which 
no  one  familiar  with  the  latest  philosophy  will 
need  to  have  demonstrated. 


VII, 

IMMORTALITY  OF  THE  SOUL. 

That  Strauss  should  regard  faith  in  immor- 
tality as  a  superstition  is  a  matter  of  course. 
It  is  only  a  logical  necessity  that  the  denial  of 
God  should  involve  the  denial  of  the  immortal- 
ity of  the  soul.  It  is  also  involved  in  the  nature 
of  the  case,  that  there  are  not  and  cannot  be 
"  evidences'^  of  the  immortality  of  the  soul,  so 
rigid  as  to  make  its  rejection  impossible.  None 
the  less  does  Strauss  demand  this  sort  of  evi- 
dence. The  result  is  that  he  discovers  that  the 
evidences  hitherto  given — the  weakest  of  which 
he  carefully  selects,  ignoring  the  stronger  ones 
— have  no  cogency.  But  in  doing  this  he  is 
simply  guilty  once  more  of  confounding  distinct 
notions.  When  evidences  are  so  rigid  as  to 
make  rejection  impossible,  we  call  the  result 
knowledge;  and  that  we  have,  in  this  sense,  a 
knowledge  of  the  immortality  of  the  soul,  no 


92      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

sober  pbilosophical  thinker  has  ever  pretended. 
The  question  here  at  issue  is  that  oi  faith  in  im- 
mortality. Faith  must  indeed  be  able  to  sustain 
itself  by  good  objective  reasons,  or  it  would  be 
nothing  more  than  a  subjective  opinion,  or  a 
superstition.  But  there  are  reasons  sufficient 
to  justify  it  which  are  nevertheless  not  coercive 
evidences,  because  doubts  and  exceptions  may 
be  urged  against  them,  the  W' eight  of  which  de- 
pends upon  the  subjectivity  of  the  individual, 
into  the  balance  of  which  they  are  cast.  Only 
on  this  account  is  it  faith,  not  knowledge.  Such 
reasons  there  are,  and  they  stand  fast,  despite 
Strauss's  confutation ;  some  of  them  in  fact  he 
has  not  touched  at  all,  [That  Strauss  should 
make  no  reference  to  the  arguments  for  the  im- 
mortality of  the  soul  w^hich  I  have  grouped  to- 
gether in  my  book,  "  God  and  Nature,''*  is 
nothing  more  than  was  to  be  expected.  The 
renow^ned  critic  confines  himself,  as  a  matter  of 
course,  to  the  renowned  old  philosophers.] 

VIII. 

THE  ESSENTIAL  NATURE  OF  RELIGION. 

Strauss  closes  his  diatribe  against  faith  in 
immortality  in  w^ords  ^vhich   sum  up   his  prin- 

^  Gott  und  die  Natur,  2  Aufl.  330  seq. 


THE   ESSENTIAL   NATURE   OF   RELIGION.        93 

ciple:  "Nothing  is  immaterial  except  that 
which  is  not  at  all."*  After  that  we  might 
expect  that  to  his  second  question,  "Have  we 
religion  still  ?"  he  would  return  as  downright  a 
negative  as  he  has  given  to  the  first.  Material- 
ists, at  least,  who  are  consistent  with  their  prin- 
ciples, have  constantly  denied  religion,  uncon- 
ditionally and  in  every  aspect.  Strauss  is  not 
ready  for  that.  He  begins  once  more  his  search 
into  "  the  essential  character  "  of  religion.  He 
justifies  Schleiemacher's  derivation  of  religion 
from  the  feeling  of  absolute  dependence.  But 
he  also  discovers  that  "  Feuerbach  is  rio'ht  in 
"saying:  The  origin,  in  fact  tlie  very  essence 
"  of  religion  is  desire.  Had  man  no  desires  he 
"would  have  no  gods.  What  man  desires  to 
"  be,  but  is  not,  he  makes  into  his  god ;  what 
"  he  would  like  to  have,  but  cannot  secure  for 
"himself,  his  god  is  to  secure  for  him.  It  is 
"  not,  therefore,  simplj^  the  dependence  in  which 
"  he  finds  himself,  but  the  need  also  of  counter- 
"  acting  it,  of  setting  himself  over  against  it,  in 
"  freedom  once  more,  from  which  religion  arises 
"among  men.^'f  At  an  earlier  point  in  his  ar- 
gument Strauss  approves  of  the  Epicurean  the- 

*  Alt.  u.  Neu.  Gl.  Sechst.  Aufl.  134 
t  P.  153,  Sechst.  Aufl.  137. 


94      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

cry,  that  fear  is  the  mother  of  religion.  Now 
he  approves  of  Feuerbach's  theory  that  the  ori- 
gin and  the  very  essence  of  religion  is  desire. 
Are  we  to  understand  by  this  that  the  dread  of 
hunger  and  want  is  identical  with  the  desire  of 
man  to  be  what  his  god  is,  or  what  he  imagines 
his  god  to  be  ?  And  is  this  desire  capable  of 
being  harmonized  \vith  the  feeling  of  absolute 
dependence  ?  Is  it  not  a  contradiction  in  the 
adjective,  first  to  depress  man  to  the  level  of  the 
animal,  w^ho  lives  and  cares  only  for  the  gratifi- 
cation of  the  wants  of  the  senses,  and  then  to 
take  this  very  same  being,  man,  in  the  very  same 
relation,  to  wit,  in  the  relation  to  religion,  and 
endow  him  with  the  desire  for  a  loftier  being, 
the  desire  for  divine  perfection,  power  and  free- 
dom ?  Is  it  not  just  as  contradictory  to  devise 
the  very  same  phenomenon  from  two  sources 
which  are  diametrically  opposite — the  feeling  of 
dependence,  and  the  need  of  freedom  ?  As- 
suredly if  man  hides  w^ithin  him  antitheses  like 
these,  if  man  have  this  duality  of  nature,  he 
cannot  be  put  upon  the  same  plane  W'ith  the 
rest  of  beings. 


THE   PERMANENT   IN   RELIGION,    ETC.  95 


IX. 

THE  PERMANENT  IN  RELIGION.      MAN,   AND  THE 
UNIVERSE. 

To  the  acknowledgment  of  this  Strauss  him- 
self is  finall}^  brought.  He  allows  religion  to 
stand  as  a  distinguishing  mark  of  human  nature 
in  its  essential  character.  Only,  "  religion  with 
us  is  no  longer  what  it  was  with  our  fathers.^' 
It  no  longer  involves  faith  in  the  existence  of  a 
God,  and  faith  in  the  immortality  of  the  soul. 
Its  origin,  and  its  essence  is  rather  a  "recog- 
nition of  the  universe,"  though  it  be  but  of  a 
very  narrow  part  of  it.  "  We  perceive  in  the 
''world  a  restless  alternation.  In  this  alterna- 
"tion,  however,  we  soon  discover  something 
"  permanent,  we  discover  order  and  law.  We 
"  perceive  in  nature  violent  antitheses,  and  fear- 
"  ful  conflicts ;  but  we  find  that  the  existence 
"  and  unison  of  the  whole  is  not  destroyed  by 
"  them,  but  is,  on  the  contrary,  preserved.  We 
"  perceive  further  a  graduation,  a  development 
"  of  the  higher  from  the  lower,  of  the  delicate 
"  from  the  coarse,  of  the  mild  from  the  harsh. 
"  We  find,  besides,  that  we  are,  ourselves,  ad- 
"  vanced  both  in  our  personal  and  social  life  in 
"proportion    as   we   succeed   in    subjecting  to 


96      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

"  rule  what  is  arbitrarily  shifting  within  us  and 
"  around  us,  in  proportion  as  from  the  lower, 
"  we  develop  the  higher,  from  the  harsh  develop 
"  the  tender.  To  this  sort  of  things,  when  we 
"  encounter  it  in  the  circle  of  human  life,  we 
"  give  the  name,  rational  and  good.  What  we 
"  perceive  in  correspondence  with  it  in  the  world 
"  around  us  we  cannot  help  calling  by  the  same 
"  names.  And  as,  besides,  we  feel  ourselves  ab- 
"  solutely  dependent  on  this  world,  as  we  derive 
"  our  existence  and  the  controlling  influence  of 
"  our  being  from  it  alone,  we  are  compelled  to 
"  regard  it  in  its  total  notion,  or  as  the  universe, 
"  as  also  the  primal  source  of  all  that  is  rational 
"  and  good.  From  the  fact  that  the  rational  and 
''good  in  the  human  race  proceeds  from  con- 
"  sciousness  and  will,  the  old  religion  drew  the 
"inference,  that  whatever  we  find  in  the  broad 
"world  correspondent  with  these  qualities  must 
"  also  have  proceeded  from  a  conscious  and 
"  voluntary  author.  We  have  abandoned  this 
"  sort  of  syllogism ;  w^e  no  longer  regard  the 
"  world  as  the  work  of  an  absolute,  rational, 
"and  beneficent  person,  but  as  the  working- 
"  place  of  the  rational  and  the  good.  It  is  to 
"  our  view  no  longer  planned  by  a  Supreme 
"  Reason,  but  planned  on  supreme  reason.  We 
"  must,  indeed,  in  this  view  also,  put  into  the 


THE   PERMANENT   IN   RELIGION,   ETC.  97 

"  cause  what  lies  in  the  effect;  what  comes  out 
*'  of  it,  must  have  been  iu  it.  But  this  is  noth- 
"ing  more  than  the  limitation  of  oar  human 
"  mode  of  conception ;  the  universe  is,  iu  fact, 
"  at  one  and  the  same  time  cause  and  effect,  ex- 

"  ternal  and  internal It  is  consequently 

"that  sometliing  on  which  we  feel  ourselves 
"  absolutely  dependent.  It  is  in  no  wise  or  man- 
"  ner  a  coarse  domineering  power,  before  which 
"we  bow  in  dumb  resignation,  but  is  at  once 
"  order  and  law,  reason  and  goodness,  to  which 
"  we  commit  ourselves  in  loving  trust.  And  yet 
"  more,  as  we  perceive  in  ourselves  that  draw- 
"  ing  to  the  rational  and  good,  which  we  believe 
"  we  perceive  in  the  world,  as  we  find  that  we 
"are  the  beings  by  whom  it  is  felt  and  recog- 
"nized,  in  whom  it  is  to  become  personal,  we 
"  feel  ourselves,  in  our  inmost  soul,  in  affinity 
"  with  that  on  which  we  find  ourselves  depend- 
"  ent — in  our  very  dependence  we  find  ourselves 
"free;  in  our  feeling  for  the  universe  pride  is 
"mingled  with  humility,  joy  with  resignation.''* 

^  P.  136  seq.  Sechst.  Aufl.  142  seq. 


98      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

X. 

THE  NEW  FAITH. 

This  "  feeling  for  the  universe"  is  Strauss's 
religion,  the  "  new  faith,"  which  is  to  set  aside 
the  old  faith. 

Strauss  himself  expresses  a  doubt  whether 
"persons"  will  allow  this  feeling  to  pass  for 
religion.  And  beyond  doubt  "persons,"  that  is, 
the  great  majority  of  those  who  associate  a  dis- 
tinct notion  w^ith  the  word  "  religion,"  will 
decline  to  bestow  it  on  this  new  faith.  But 
Strauss  cares  little  for  names,  and  hence  to  the 
question,  Whether  "we"  have  religion  still? 
his  reply  is,  "Yes  or  no,  just  as  persons  are 
inclined  to  take  it." 

To  us  also  the  name  is  a  matter  of  little  mo- 
ment, but  the  more  do  we  attach  importance  to  the 
true  notion  and  the  grounds  on  which  it  is  estab- 
lished. We  do  not  deny  that  Strauss  possesses 
the  feeling  for  the  universe  to  which  he  laj^s 
claim,  nor  that  he  believes  in  the  correctness  of 
the  conceptions  out  of  which  that  feeling  springs 
up  in  his  breast.  But  we  do  maintain  that  these 
conceptions  and  assumptions  are  not  only  ex- 
tremely vague  and  superficial,  but  that  they 
contradict  each  other  in  manifold  respects,  as 


THE   NEW   FAITH.  99 

they  also  contradict  the  assertions  involving  his 
whole  principle,  which  he  makes  in  various 
other  places.  It  is  one  marked  feature  that 
what  is  inexorably  demanded  by  logic,  he  treats 
as  "the  limitation  of  our  human  mode  of  con- 
ception." He  acknowledges  that  "  we  must  put 
into  the  cause  also,  what  lies  in  the  effect,"  and 
consequently  that  if  the  world  be  "  the  working- 
place  of  the  rational  and  good,"  we  are  com- 
pelled  to  suppose  that  for  the  rational  and  good 
which  is  effected  there  must  also  be  a  cause;  and 
that  we  cannot  avoid  conceiving  of  the  cause  as 
different  from  the  effect,  the  external  as  different 
from  the  internal.  But  inasmuch  as  this  pitiful 
logical  necessity  is  nothing  more  than  a  limita- 
tion of  our  human  mode  of  conception,  the  uni- 
verse is,  "  at  one  and  the  same  time^  cause  and 
effect,  external  and  internal."  We  are  "  com- 
pelled^^^  indeed,  to  distinguish  the  two,  and 
consequently  are  unable  to  think  one  and  the 
same  thing,  as  at  one  and  the  same  time,  cause 
and  effect;  but  as  this  is  merely  the  result  of  the 
limitation  just  spoken  of,  we  totally  disregard 
it,  and  proclaim  the  truth,  which  we  have  no 
power  of  thinking,  proclaim  it  in  words,  desti- 
tute of  all  meaning,  but  none  the  less  sonorous  I 
Strauss  does  not  consider  that  we  may  with 
equal  propriety,  speak  of  the  truth  of  wooden 


100     STRAUSS   AS    A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

iron,  or  of  a  four-cornered  triangle,  and,  to  come 
more  closelj^home  to  him  still,  that  the  doctrine 
of  the  Trinity,  which  he  so  decidedly  contests, 
on  the  ground  that  three  cannot  be  one,  can 
make  a  direct  appeal  to  him,  and  can,  with  equal 
propriety,  assert  that  this  logical  distinction  of 
one  and  three  is  nothing  more  than  a  limitation 
of  our  human  mode  of  thinking. 

XI. 

THE   DISCOYERY. 

The  "discovery"  that  in  the  world  there  is 
not  only  order  and  law,  but  also  that  there  is  a 
''development  of  the  higher  from  the  lower,  of 
''the  delicate  from  the  coarse,  of  the  mild  from 
"the  harsh/'  and  that  this  higher  something, 
this  delicacy,  mildness  or  tenderness,  when  we 
find  it  in  the  circle  of  human  life,  is  the  "ra- 
tional and  good,"  this  discovery  is  the  basis  of 
Strauss's  new  religion.  The  "we,"  in  whose 
name  he  speaks,  will  no  doubt  rest  with  entire 
satisfaction  in  this  discovery.  But  the  scientific 
investigator,  and  especially  the  philosophical 
thinker,  have  the  preposterous  whim  of  declin- 
ing to  be  put  off  with  mere  words;  they  will  in- 
sist on  asking  after  their  meaning  and  force. 
And  we  ask,  accordingly,  what  is  that  "higher 


THE   DISCOVERY.  -  101 

something,  that  delicacy  and  mildness,"  of 
which  Strauss  is  speaking?  In  what  way  is  it 
to  be  distinguished  from  the  low,  the  coarse, 
the  harsh?  As  Strauss  leaves  us  without  a 
reply,  we  should  be  compelled,  on  this  ground, 
were  there  no  other,  to  deny  that  the  at- 
tempt at  establishing  the  new  religion  has  any 
scientific  value  whatever.  Higher  and  lower, 
coarse  and  delicate,  harsh  and  mild,  are  desig- 
nations whose  tenor  is  so  indefinite,  so  relative 
and  slight,  that  unless  they  be  accurately  de- 
fined they  amount  to  nothing.  And  why  is  it 
that  the  delicate,  mild  little  squirrel  is  more 
rational,  and  is  better  than  the  coarse,  rough 
swine?  Why  is  the  humming-bird  better  than 
the  owl?  Why  is  the  butterfly  better  than  the 
cockchafer?  Why  is  the  rose  better  than  the 
thistle?  The  professed  materialist,  to  whom 
everything  is  blind  necessity  and  conformity  to 
law,  has  no  right  to  make  distinctions  either 
between  higher  and  lower,  between  coarse  and 
delicate,  or  between  the  rational  and  irrational, 
the  good  and  the  bad.  What  is  the  product  of 
blind  necessity  is  equally  high  and  low,  equally 
rational  and  irrational,  equally  good  and  bad, 
because  it  is  neither  the  one  nor  the  other. 
The  fact  that  materialism  does  not  see  the  con- 
tradiction in  which  it  involves  itself,  in  impos- 

4 


102      STRAUSS  AS  A  PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

ing  on  a  blind,  unconscious,  unthinking  neces- 
sity, the  adjustment  of  a  development  of  a 
higher  something  out  of  a  lower,  the  control- 
ling with  reason  and  goodness,  this  fact  allows 
of  but  one  solution.  The  solution  is  found  in 
the  superficiality  and  lack  of  thought  which 
seem  to  cleave  inevitably  to  that  system.  For 
such  a  control  as  this  view  concedes,  presupposes 
of  necessity  a  distinction  between  the  higher  and 
the  lower,  the  good  and  the  bad.  The  lower 
must  from  the  beginning  have  been  so  designed 
that  the  higher  could  shape  itself  out  of  it;  it 
must  consequently  have  been  originally  placed 
in  relation  to  the  higher  something,  and  must 
have  been  determined  in  conformity  with  it. 
But  how  does  it  come  to  avoid  the  irrational,  or 
to  carry  on  a  training  which  results  in  the 
rational,  inasmuch  as  there  is  no  distinction 
w^hatever  between  the  two?  The  rational  and 
irrational  are  not  things  which  the  hand  can 
grasp;  there  is  no  such  thing  as  rational  or 
irrational  matter.  The  rational  and  irrational 
is  nothing  at  all  material,  nothing  phenomenal, 
nothing  addressing  our  sense  perceptions.  It 
is  a  something  which  is  to  be  inferred  from  cer- 
tain given  conceptions.  The  rational  is  there- 
fore itself  conception,  it  is  nothing  but  conception, 
which  we  shape  to  ourselves  mainly  from  our 


THE   DISCOVERY.  103 

own  attitude,  our  willing  and  thinking  over  our 
conduct  in  its  ethical  relations.  The  power  of 
deriving  this  conception  from  the  facts  of  con- 
sciousness, and  of  thinking,  willing  and  acting 
in  conformity  with  it,  we  call  reason.  Where 
there  is  no  thinking,  willing  and  acting,  in  an 
ethical  respect,  there  is  consequently  no  rea- 
son ;  the  use  of  the  term  is  an  abuse.  Of  the 
reason  of  nature  and  the  rationality  of  nature 
we  know  nothing  at  all  originally.  We  trans- 
fer them  to  nature,  because  we  believe  we  rec- 
ognize in  it  a  similar  bearing  of  things  and 
events  to  each  other,  a  similar  order  and  har- 
mony, an  activity  involving  plan  and  aim,  pro- 
ceeding from  similar  motives,  directed  to  the 
preservation  of  the  whole,  and  to  the  promo- 
tion of  the  interests  of  the  individual  parts. 
But  in  this  very  process  we  impute  to  nature 
the  conception  of  the  rational,  and  of  a  think- 
ing, w^illing  and  acting  derived  from  that 
conception^  and  we  can  talk  no  longer  of  blind 
necessity.  The  consistent  materialist  who 
knows  what  he  is  talking  of,  is  necessarily 
a  casualist  in  the  strict  sense,  that  is,  he  holds 
that  the  seeming  conformity  to  law,  the  order, 
the  rationalitj^,  whether  in  nature  or  in  human 
life,  are  either  mere  seeming  and  illusion,  or 
the  fortuitous  result  of  fortuitous  combinations 


104      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

of  fortuitously  existing  matter,  out  of  fortuit- 
ously occurring  operations,  which  just  as  fortu- 
itously may  at  any  moment,  separate,  fall  to 
pieces,  or  enter  into  new  combinations.  If  in 
spite  of  all  this  he  is  determined  to  have  religion 
still,  he  has  nothing  left  to  worship  but  insen- 
sate Chance. 

XII. 

THE  GOOD  AKD  THE  BAD. 

And  what  right  furthermore  has  Strauss  to 
draw  a  distinction  between  good  and  bad?  We 
can  only  speak  of  good  in  the  ethical  sense  on 
the  assumption  of  the  freedom  of  the  will.  And 
a  being  in  absolute  dependence  on  nature,  and 
its  laws,  cannot  even  in  the  most  contracted 
sense  be  called  free.  It  is  certainly  beyond  all 
comprehension  how  such  a  being  can  ever  go 
so  far  as  to  "react''  against  his  ''absolute  de- 
pendence,''  and  strive  after  freedom.  Certainly 
this  striving  is  a  gross  error,  a  treacherous  illu- 
sion, and  that  reaction  can  be  nothing  more 
than  a  purely  impotent  outrage.  The  good  in 
Strauss's  new  religion  can  therefore  be  nothing 
more  than  the  feeling  of  pleasure,  the  agreeable, 
the  useful.  With  it  coincides  then,  as  a  matter 
of  course,  the  rational,  for  these  two  notions 
Strauss  identifies.     His  only  reason,  therefore. 


THE   GOOD   AND   THE   BAD.  105 

for  regarding  the  delicate,  mild  and  tender  as 
good,  is  that  he  supposes  that  these  are  more 
agreeable,  delightful  and  beneficial  than  their 
opposites.  The  great  majority  of  men,  however, 
find  themselves  much  more  comfortable  in  what 
is  gross  and  coarse,  than  in  what  is  fine  and 
tender;  they  regard  a  coarse  license  as  far  more 
agreeable  than  subjection  to  law,  and  the  bad, 
as  in  many  cases,  more  useful  than  the  good. 
With  w^hat  right  then  does  Strauss  maintain 
that  the  opposite  is  good?  When  the  sensuous 
material  man  of  Strauss's  description  finds  him- 
self pained  by  the  law,  order  and  reason,  which 
sway  in  the  universe,  why  should  he  persist  in 
calling  them  good?  In  fact  we  have  once  more 
a  gross  contradiction  of  Strauss's  own  premises 
when  he  pronounces  the  "coarse  domineering 
power,"  the  coarse  dissoluteness,  to  be  evil, 
while  on  the  other  hand,  the  "resignation^'  to 
the  order  and  reason  which  sway  in  the  universe 
is  good.  He  even  goes  beyond  this  and  de- 
fines man  as  the  being  in  whom  the  rational 
and  good  "is  to  become  personal."  Yet,  after 
all  this,  he  gainsays  the  claim  of  this  very  be- 
ing, man,  to  soul,  freedom,  morality.  A  be- 
ing "absolutely  dependent"  on  nature  and  its 
laws,  cannot  feel  that  nature's  power  is  "a  coarse 
domineering,"  cannot  subject  himself  to  it,  either 


106      STRAUSS  AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

in  "dumb  resignation/'  or  "with  loving  trust." 
For  if  no  real  possibility  of  transgressing  the 
law,  coexist  with  the  law%  subjection  under  law 
is  no  5^//-subjection,  no  ^^//'-surrender,  but  is 
simply  an  unconditioned  state  of  subjection. 


XIII. 

STRAUSS  IN  CONFLICT  WITH  CONSISTENT  MATERIAL- 
ISM;  pessimism;  Schopenhauer,  yon  hartmann. 

The  consistent  materialists,  therefore,  who  do 
not  find  in  the  world  embodied  reason  and  good- 
ness, are  regarded  by  Strauss  as  his  opponents, 
though  in  other  respects  they  are  in  complete 
harmony  with  his  principles.  He  therefore  re- 
sorts to  sharp  w^eapons  in  his  battle  with  the 
Pessimism  of  Schopenhauer  and  Von  Hart- 
mann. He  finds  in  them,  as  he  does  in  every 
pessimistic  view  of  the  w^orld,  ''  the  grossest 
contradiction."  For  "  if  this  world  is  a  thing 
''  which  had  better  not  be,  then,  forsooth,  the 
''  thinking  of  philosophers,  which  forms  a  part 
"of  this  world,  is  a  thinking  which  had  better 
"not  be  thought.  The  pessimist  philosopher 
"  does  not  notice  how,  more  than  all,  he  declares 
"  as  bad  his  own  thinking,  which  declares  the 
''  world  to  bo  bad;  but  if  a  thinking?  which  de- 


PESSIMISM.  107 

"  clares  the  world  to  be  bad  is  bad  thiiikiug, 
"  then  it  follows,  on  the  contrary,  that  the  world 
"  is  good.  Optimism  may,  as  a  rule,  make  its 
"  own  task  a  little  too  easy;  and  in  this  aspect 
"  Schopenhauer's  proof  of  the  tremendous  part 
"played  by  pain  and  evil  in  the  world  are  en- 
'^  tirely  in  place;  but  every  true  philosophy  is 
"  necessarily  optimistic,  as  in  any  other  theory 
"  it  denies  its  own  right  to  existence  (it  saws  off 
''  the  branch  on  which  it  is  sitting).''"^  This 
criticism  is  entirely  convincing.  But  does  it 
not  involve  Strauss's  own  philosophy  and  the 
new  religion  he  has  built  on  it  ?  If  nothing  but 
the  delicate,  the  mild,  the  tender  is  good,  is 
there  not  at  least  as  much  of  the  gross,  the 
coarse,  the  harsh  in  the  world?  And  if  good 
be  no  more  than  the  secular  well-being  of  man, 
who  is  thoroughly  earthy  and  material,  is  not 
every  one  with  whom,  in  his  own  estimation, 
things  have  gone  badly  on  the  whole,  or  at  least 
not  as  well  as  they  ought  to  have  gone,  entirely 
justified  in  maintaining  that  the  subsisting  regu- 
lation of  the  world  is  bad  ?  Is  he  not  at  least 
on  as  defensible  ground  as  that  taken  by  the 
optimist  with  the  opposite  view  ?  To  say  noth- 
ing,  then,   of  the   internal    contradictions    of 

*  P.  142,  Sechst.  Aufl.  147. 


108     STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

Strauss's  view,  does  he  not  make  his  own  task 
a  little  "  too  easy"  when  he  grounds  his  optim- 
ism on  the  "discoveries*^  which  have  been 
stated  ? 

XIV. 

"what  is  our  apprehension  of  the  universe?" 

After  Strauss  has  laid  the  basis  of  religion 
in  general,  only  on  our  knowledge  of  the  world, 
and  the  feeling  which  springs  from  it,  he  at- 
tempts in  the  third  division  an  answer  to  the 
question,  "  What  is  our  apprehension  of  the 
universe?'^  He  applies  himself  forthwith  to 
the  knotty,  much-mooted  problem,  whether  the 
universe  is  to  be  conceived  of  as  infinite  or 
finite.  He  decides  that  it  is  infinite,  but  again 
without  telling  us  what  he  means  by  infinity. 
And  yet  the  old  controversy  was  caused  by  a 
failure  on  the  part  of  the  combatants  to  attempt 
to  come  to  an  understanding  in  advance  in  ref- 
erence to  the  notion  of  the  infinite.  If  we  take 
the  word  in  a  purely  negative  sense,  and  such 
a  sense  the  word  itself  involves,  it  is  evident 
that  the  infinite,  as  the  negation  of  the  finite, 
or  limited,  not  only  presupposes  the  finite  of 
which  it  is  the  negation,  but  is  in  itself  nothing 
but  negation,  and  is,  consequently,  yiothing.  To 
speak  of  a  primordial  something,  infinite  in  itself 


OUR   APPEEHENSION   OF   THE   UNIVERSE.      109 

in  this  sense,  whether  we  suppose  it  to  be  the 
Deity  or  the  universe,  is  consequently  a  contra- 
diction in  the  adjective.  The  finite,  it  is  true, 
involves  also  a  negation ;  it  is,  ihdeed,  a  posi- 
tive, an  existent  by  another  existent,  but  with  a 
negation,  a  bound  or  limitation,  attached  to  it, 
and  is,  consequently,  a  being  which  in  itself  in- 
volves a  non-being.  The  first  problem,  conse- 
quently, is  to  define,  to  determine  the  notion  of 
the  finite.  This  involves  the  solution  of  the  old 
Eleatic  question,  How  can  being  coexist  with 
non-being?  Had  Strauss  thoroughly  reflected 
on  this  question,  he  would  have  discovered  that 
no  answer  to  it  is  possible,  except  by  the  notion 
of  distinction  and  of  distinguishing  activity  as 
the  fundamental  and  primal  activitj'^  of  all  think- 
ing, or  consciousness,  and  as  the  determining 
primal  force  of  all  that  is  in  being.  Instead  of 
this,  without  anything  further,  he  proclaims  the 
infiniteness  of  the  world,  and  imagines  that  he 
has  solved  the  problem  by  making  a  distinction 
between  "  world  in  the  absolute  sense,  that  is, 
"  the  universe,  and  world  in  the  relative  sense 
''in  which  it  has  a  plural."  Thereupon  he 
maintains  that  "  though  it  is  true  that  every 
"world  in  the  latter  sense,  through  parts  of  the 
"  totality  in  its  widest  compass,  has  its  limita- 
''tion  in  space  as  it  has  its  beginning  and  end 


110      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

'  in  time,  yet  the  universe  spreads  itself  forth 
'and  maintains  its  continnitj^  inimitably,  alike 
'  through  all  space  and  all  time."*  "  Conse- 
'  quentlj'  not  6nly  our  earth,  but  our  solar  system 
'  also,  and  every  other  part  of  the  totality  of  the 
'  universe,  has  at  one  period  been  what  it  no 
'  longer  is  [in  this  sort  did  not  exist  at  all],  and 
'will  one  day  cease  to  be  as  it  is  now,"  but  as 
to  the  universe  "  there  never  was  a  time  when 
'  it  was  not,  a  time  when  there  was  in  it  no 
'  distinction  of  celestial  bodies,  no  life,  no  rea- 
'  son.  All  this,  if  it  was  not  in  one  part  of  the 
'  totality,  was  in  another  part,  and  had  ceased 
'  to  be  in  a  third  part ;  here  it  was  coming  into 
'  being,  there  it  was  in  full  subsistence,  in  a 
'  third  place  it  was  passing  away;  the  universe 
'  is  an  infinite  complex  of  worlds  in  all  the 
'stadia  of  origin  and  transition, and  because  of 
'  this  eternal  revolution  and  alternation  pre- 
'  serves  itself  in  eternal  absolute  fulness  of 
'  life."f  This  train  of  thought  is  essentially  that 
of  Kant.  Strauss  has,  in  his  own  opinion,  im- 
proved upon  it,  but  in  reality  has  made  it  worse 
in  the  mending,  by  throwing  out  the  notion  of 
creation  and  of  God,  and  With  this  he  imagines 

^  Sechst.  Aufl.  152. 

t  P.  148  seq.  Sechst.  Aufl.  153. 


OUR   APPREHENSION   OF   THE   UNIVERSE.      Ill 

be  has  disposed  of  the  whole  matter.  But  is  not 
an  "z^yHimited"  whole,  made  up  of  nothing  but 
limiled  parts,  be  they  celestial  bodies  or  atoms, 
a  glaring  contradiction  in  the  adjective?  Is 
there  not  a  palpable  contradiction  in  this  de- 
scription of  a  totalit}^  in  which  at  every  time, 
and  consequently  at  07ie  and  the  same  time,  a  part 
coming  into  being,  subsists  and  has  subsisted 
by  the  side  of  one  which  has  already  come  into 
being?  The  part  which  has  come  into  being 
must,  nevertheless,  also  at  one  time  have  been 
in  the  course  of  coming  into  being,  must  conse- 
quently have  been  in  being  before  the  part  which 
is  just  coming  into  being,  and  consequently  as 
something  in  actual  being  cannot  be  associated 
as  simultaneous  \\\\\\  what  is  just  coming  into 
being.  In  other  words,  just  as  little  as  we  are 
in  a  condition  to  think  of  an  infinite  whole  with 
nothing  but  finite  parts,  that  is,  a  finite  infinite- 
ness  or  an  infinite  finiteness,  just  as  little  can 
we  think  of  an  activity  which  is  in  a  purely  nega- 
tive sense  eternal,  that  is,  absolutely  without  be- 
ginning. For  the  act  proceeding  from  such  an 
activity  must  likewise  be  simply  without  begin- 
ning, as  an  activity  without  something  to  do  is 
no  activity.  But  we  can  only  think  of  the  act 
as  the  result  of  the  activity,  the  activity  only  as 
prior  to  the  act.     The  act  begins  consequently  of 


112     STRAUSS  AS  A   PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

necessity  by  and  with  the  activity;  an  act  with- 
out beginning  is  a  contradiction  in  the  adjective, 
as  that  would  mean  an  act  without  activity,  an 
effect  w^ithout  a  cause.  It  follows  also  that  an  ac- 
tivity without  beginning  is  a  contradiction  in  the 
adjective,  for  that,  as  an  act  without  beginning, 
is  impossible,  and  would  be  an  activity  without 
an  act,  a  cause  without  an  effect.  For  this  very 
reason  then  we  can  conceive  a  beginning  which 
is  positive,  the  absolute  antecedent  of  all  origin 
and  of  all  that  is  originated,  of  all  doing  and 
of  all  that  comes  to  pass,  and  which  on  this  very 
account  has  no  beginning  in  another.  In  fact 
we  are  compelled  to  accept  such  an  absolute  an- 
tecedent, inasmuch  as  the  unbesrinnine:,  the 
simple  negation  of  beginning,  involves  as  its 
own  presupposition  the  very  thing  it  denies,  and 
consequently  involves  the  thought  of  absolute 
beginning.  If  Strauss,  then,  does  not  mean  to 
insist  that  a  finiteness  without  end,  an  act  with- 
out activity,  is  conceivable,  he  will  have  to 
abandon  the  infiniteness  and  eternity  of  his 
universe,  and  will  have  to  concede  the  positively 
infinite,  as  that  which  sets  all  limitation  and 
bounds,  all  greatness,  and  all  measure  (by  dis- 
tinction), and  the  positively  eternal  as  the  abso- 
lute antecedent  of  all  origin  and  of  all  that  is 
originated,  of  all  doing  and  of  all  that  comes  to 
pass,  and  hence  of  the  world  itself. 


THE   COSMOGONY   OF   KANT  AND   LA   PLACE.      113 

XY. 

THE  COSMOGONY  OF  KANT  AND  LA  PLACE. 

In  order  to  show  how  we  may  apprehend  the 
origination  of  a  world,  in  the  '^  relative  "  sense 
of  the  word,  without  the  interference  of  a 
higher  and  divine  power,  Strauss  goes  on  to 
develop  in  his  own  fashion  the  familiar  hypothe- 
sis by  which  Kant  and  La  Place  explained  the 
rise  and  development  of  our  solar  system.  [The 
proof  I  have  presented  that  this  self-origination 
and  self-development  without  a  prirniim  movens 
et  deierminans — a  primary  mover  and  determi- 
ner— is  inconceivable,*  Strauss,  as  a  matter  of 
course,  again  fails  to  notice.  He  notices,  never- 
theless, some  of  the  facts  which  are  in  decided 
conflict  with  the  hypothesis,  but  he  puts  them 
all  aside  with  the  wei^-htv  remark :  ''  This  be- 
longs  to  those  inexactnesses  in  the  results  of 
nature  of  which  Kant  speaks  !"t]  It  would 
far  transcend  the  proper  limits  of  an  article  in 
a  Review  to  follow  with  our  criticism  each  step 
of  Strauss's  exposition.  We  shall  confine  our 
notices  therefore  to  a  few  untenable  positions 
taken  by  him  in  the  sphere  of  the  natural  sci- 

*  Ulrici :  Gott  u.  die  Natur,  Zweit.  Aufl.  337-353. 
t  Alt.  u.  Neu.  Glaub.  158. 


114      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

ences.  It  is  inadmissible  to  argue  from  tlie 
shortening  of  the  track  of  a  comet  (Enke's)  to 
the  orbit  of  the  planets,  the  shortening  of  which 
has  not  to  this  hour  been  established  by  any 
reliable  observation.  For  out  of  the  demon- 
strated fact  of  the  division  of  Biela's  comet,  in 
1845j  it  is  evident  that  under  some  circum- 
stances the  comets  may  be  diminished  in  bulk. 
The  comet  thus  divided  did  not  reappear  in 
1866,  nor  in  1872,  when  it  could  not  have  failed 
to  be  observed.  Instead  of  that,  in  November, 
1872,  there  was  observed  a  fall  of  a  great  num- 
ber of  shooting  stars,  which  previously  had 
moved  in  the  track  about  the  sun  in  which 
Biela's  comet  had  kept,  rendering  it  highly 
probable  that  the  comet  had  gone  to  fragments, 
and  that  under  certain  conditions  of  the  masses 
of  matter  of  which  comets  are  composed,  they 
may  be  completely  sundered  so  as  to  go  to  pieces. 
With  the  diminution  of  the  mass  the  track  is 
necessarily  shortened.  Strauss  is  mistaken 
when  he  goes  on  to  assert:  "Assuming,  with 
*'Kant  and  La  Place,  the  mass  of  nebular  ex- 
"  tended  matter  as  the  relative  primal  matter  of 
"  our  planetary  system,  we  conceive,  even  if  we 
"  suppose  it  to  be  derived  from  a  previous  pro- 
"  cess  of  combustion,  that  it  was  completely 
"cooled  because  of  its  extreme  disgregation.'^ 


ORIGIN  OF   LIFE   UPON   EARTH.  115 

Conformably  with  this  we  have  to  assume  that 
the  scattered  atoms  "  did  not  attain  heat  and 
"luminositj^  until  they  approximated  under  the 
"law  of  gravitation."  For  it  is  established  by 
natural  science,  that  the  ponderable  forms  of 
matter — apart  from  the  few  permanent  gases — 
are  resolved  into  masses  of  vapor,  or  pass  into 
"  disgregation  "  only  in  consequence  of  increas- 
ing heat,  and  require  sustained  heat  to  be  kept 
in  that  condition.  With  the  beo-innins;  of  the 
cooling,  gravitation  and  chemical  attraction 
come  into  corresponding  activity.  That  the 
primary  matter  should  be  "  completely  cooled 
oflV  and  should  yet  be  a  nebulous  mass,  is  a 
thing  which  natural  science  shows  to  be  impos- 
sible. It  is  equally  false  that  "the  revolving 
"motion  is  natural  to  a  spherical  mass  consist- 
"  ing  of  matter  in  the  form  of  vapor  or  of  fluid." 
On  the  contrary,  it  is  a  universally  acknowledged 
theorem  that  no  ponderable  mass  simply  of  itself^ 
without  a  force  moving  it,  sets  itself  in  motion, 
either  of  a  rotary  character  or  of  any  other. 

XVI. 

ORIGIN  OF  LIFE  UPON  EARTH— GENERATIO  ^QUI- 
YOCA.      ORGANIC  AND  INORGANIC. 

With  a  quick  turn  Strauss  finishes  up  the 
development  of  our  terrestrial  globe,  and  goes 


116      STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

on  to  the  question  in  regard  to  the  origination  of 
organisms  or  "living  substances.''*  Though  he 
admits  that  "in  consequence  of  the  difficulty  of 
"  making  conclusive  experiments,  a  general  deci- 
"sion  has  not  yet  been  reached/'  he  yet  decides 
without  hesitation  for  the  generatio  oequivoca  or 
spontanea.  He  reduces  the  question  to  this 
shape:  "Whether  it  is  possible  that  an  indi- 
"vidual  organism,  even  of  the  least  perfect  sort, 
"  can  arise  in  any  other  way  than  through  its 
"own  like?  can  arise,  to  wit,  by  chemical  or 
"  morphologic  processes,  which  take  place  not 
"  in  the  egg^  or  in  the  womb,  but  in  other  forms 
"  of  matter,  in  organic  or  inorganic  fluids."t 

ViRCHOW  says  that  all  known  facts  give  their 
testimony  against  spontaneous  generation  in  our 
day.  To  meet  this  Strauss  resorts  to  "entirely 
"  extraordinary  conditions,  in  the  era  of  the 
"greater  revolutions  of  the  earth,"  that  out  of 
them  life  may  come  forth,  ''of  course,  in  its  yet 
incompletest  form,'^  of  which  the  Bathybius  and 
Moneres  are  examples.  This  coming  forth  con- 
sists in  the  "  special  movement  of  the  matter, 
"  through  which,  from  time  to  time,  a  part  of 
"  collective  matter  withdraws,  from  the  ordinary 
"  course  of  its  movements,  into  special  organico- 

^  P.  167,  Sechst.  Aufl.  171. 
t  P.  169,  Sechst.  Aufl.  173. 


OEIGIN   OF   LIFE   UPON   EARTH.  117 

"  chemical  combinations.  In  this  state  it  remains 
"  for  a  time,  and  then  reverts  to  the  general  re- 
"lations  of  movement."*  ''If  the  question  be 
"properly  regarded/^  continues  Strauss,  "it 
"  does  not  involve  the  creation  of  something  new, 
but  only  the  bringing  of  existent  forms  of  mat- 
ter and  forces  into  another  species  of  combina- 
tion and  movement,  and  for  this  a  sufficient 
occasion  may  be  found,  in  the  conditions  of 
"  primeval  time,  so  totally  diverse  from  those  of 
"  the  present,  the  wholly  different  temperature, 
"  and  of  atmospheric  composition,  and  similar 
*'causes.'^t 

Strauss  forgets  that  but  a  few  pages  before  he 
has  observed :  "  The  geology  of  our  day  is  in- 
"  clined  to  construe  the  details  of  the  formation 
"  of  our  earth  far  more  in  accordance  with  ordi- 
"  nary  method,  far  more  in  accordance  with  what 
"we  see  at  present  in  the  course  of  nature. "J 
And,  in  fact,  the  geology  of  our  day,  subsequent 
to  Lyell,  is  not  only  "inclined'^  thus  "to  con- 
strue" the  details,  but  has  pretty  clearly  demon- 
strated that  it  is  precisely  in  this  way  things 
actually  came  to  pass.  The  appeal  to  "  the  con- 
ditions of  primeval  time,"  so  totally  diverse  from 

■^  Yircbow. 

t  Sechst.  Aufl.  175. 

X  Sechst.  Aufl.  171. 


118     STRAUSS  AS   A  PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

those  of  the  present,  is  an  evasion  which  is  no 
longer  allowable,  especially  as  it  is  an  estab- 
lished fact,  that  a  "wholly  different  tempera- 
ture," that  is,  one  higher  than  the  tropical,  the 
highest  degree  now  known,  as  well  as  a  "differ- 
ent atmospheric  composition,"  does  not  farther 
organic  life,  but,  on  the  contrarj^,  destroys  it. 
But  were  we  to  grant  that  life  consists  only  in 
that  special  movement  of  a  part  of  "  collective 
matter,"  and  that  the  conditions  of  primeval 
time  furnish  a  sufficient  occasion  for  the  origi- 
nation of  that  movement,  the  question  still  re- 
mains to  be  answered,  Y/hy  is  it  but  "  a  part?" 
Why  does  not  the  entire  collective  matter,  at 
disposal,  and  fitted  for  this  special  movement, 
enter  on  it?  Another  question  forces  itself  on 
us.  Why  does  this  part  remain  only  "for  a 
time"  in  these  special  organico-chemical  com- 
binations, and  then  revert  to  the  general  rela- 
tions of  movement?  Besides,  it  is  false  that 
the  "living  substance"  consists  merely  in  a  spe- 
cial organico-chemical  combination  of  matter. 
On  the  contrary,  the  question  is  urgent.  How 
can  an  or2:anico-chemical  combination  of  diverse 
atoms,  oxj^gen,  hydrogen,  nitrogen,  carbon,  and 
others,  come  to  live  ?  To  reach  this  involves 
more  than  the  entrance  of  this  or  that  set  of 
atoms  into  an  organico-chemical  combination  by 


ORIGIN   OF   LIFE   UPON   EARTH.  119 

means  of  special  movement,  and  then  remaining 
for  a  time  in  the  combination.  Sugar,  urine,  cy- 
anogen, ethal,  and  other  substances,  are  organico- 
chemical  combinations,  but  they  are  not  organ- 
isms, they  are  not ''  living  substances."  Every 
organism,  even  of  the  very  lowest  grade,  even  the 
Bathybius  and  the  Moneres,  exercises  distinct 
functions.  It  is  compelled  to  preserve  itself,  to 
nourish  itself,  to  keep  off  certain  matter  from 
itself,  to  draw  other  matter  to  it,  to  take  it  into 
itself,  to  propagate  itself.  Without  this  it  would 
not  subsist  for  a  moment.  With  the  cessation 
of  this  spontaneity,  itself  and  its  kind  would 
cease  to  exist.  These  functions,  these  "  spe- 
cial" movements  are  found  in  organized  matter 
only,  never  in  unorganized.  It  is  these,  not  what 
are  called  the  organico-chemical  combinations  of 
certain  forms  of  matter  which  constitute  the  most 
general  and  essential  marks  of  every  ''living  sub- 
stance," and  of  the  living  substance  only.  They 
too,  then,  must  have  a  cause.  And  as  they  are 
''  special"  processes,  deviating  from  the  general 
conditions  of  movement,  as  it  is  an  established 
fact  that  the  chemical  substances  within  the  or- 
ganic combinations  exhibit  different  activities 
from  those  they  possess  outside  of  them,  we  are 
compelled  to  suppose  a  "special"  cause  for  these 
special  processes.     Whether  we  call  this  cause 


120     STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

vital  force,  or  give  it  whatever  name  we  please, 
so  long  as  the  chemist  fails  in  generating  in  his 
laboratory,  from  purely  inorganic  substances,  a 
"  living  substance,"  a  solitary  organism,  even  of 
the  very  lowest  order,  so  long  will  he  fail  to  re- 
move either  the  distinction  between  an  organ- 
ism and  a  mere  chemical  combination  of  matter, 
whether  of  an  organic  or  inorganic  nature,  or 
the  distinction  between  a  living  being  and  a 
complicated  machine.  So  long,  at  least,  will 
every  man  cling  to  that  distinction,  who  does 
not  one  day  acknowledge  and  the  next  day 
deny  the  law  of  causality,  as  a  legitimate  law  of 
thought. 

XVII. 

ORIGIK  OF  SPECIES.      THE  DARWINIAN  THEORY. 

In  the  much-mooted  question  of  the  origin  of 
species,  Strauss,  as  has  already  been  intimated, 
is  an  enthusiastic  adherent  of  Darwin.  He  ac- 
knowledges, indeed,  that  the  Darwinian  theory 
is  "still  extremely  imperfect;"  "it  leaves  infi- 
"nitely  much  unexplained,  and  in  the  unex- 
"  plained  are  not  merely  subordinate  matters, 
"but  what  are  reallj^  chief  and  cardinal  points; 
"he  rather  hints  at  solutions  which  may  be  pos- 
"sible  in  the  future,  than  gives  them  himself." 
Still  Strauss  claims  that  the  theory  is  a  grand 


ORIGIN   OF   SPECIES.  121 

advance,  full  of  significance.  For  Darwin  "has 
"opened  the  door  through  which  the  happier 
"world  that  is  to  follow  us  will  throw  out  all 
"nriiracle  never  to  return.  Whoever  is  aware 
"how  much  hangs  on  the  idea  of  miracle,  will 
"  thank  him  for  this  as  one  of  the  greatest  bene- 
"  factors  of  our  race.""^ 

It  is  an  extraordinary  thing  that  the  great 
critic  never  turns  the  edge  of  his  criticism 
against  himself,  his  own  opinions  and  preju- 
dices, his  own  sympathies  and  antipathies  !  It 
is  not  diflicult  to  comprehend  that  the  author  of 
"The  Life  of  Jesus'^  has  no  affection  for  theo- 
logical miracles.  But  is  it  allowable,  for  the 
gratification  of  this  antipathy,  to  laud  as  the 
greatest  and  most  beneficent  of  discoveries,  a 
theory  which  leaves  unexplained  "what  are 
really  chief  and  cardinal  points,"  and  which 
consequently  is,  in  fact,  no  theory  at  all,  only 
because  in  Strauss^s  judgment  it  does  away 
with  the  idea  of  miracle?  Is  it  admissible,  in 
favor  of  such  a  theory,  to  confound  notions 
which  are  widely  different?  Yet  this  is  the 
very  thing  which  Strauss  does.  Led  by  this 
antipathy  he  confounds  the  theological  miracles, 
such  for  example  as  that  of  the  wedding-feast 

*  P.  177,Seclist.  Aufl.  181. 


122     STRAUSS   AS   A    PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

at  Ciina,  and  others  of  its  class,  with  the  mira- 
cles of  natural  science;  that  is,  with  the  incom- 
prehensible fact  which  natural  science  is  inca- 
pable of  explaining. 

The  older  theory  assumed  that  the  lowest 
genera  and  species  of  organic  being  arose  from 
a  force  not  assignable  to  nature,  consequently^ 
a  supernatural  cause,  a  metaphysical  force. 
Darwin  maintains  that  organic  being  involves 
separate  evolutions,  and  that  the  higher  have 
arisen  from  the  lower  by  gradual  transforma- 
tion. The  old  view  certainly  was  not  able  to 
explain  the  precedency  in  question;  it  was  not 
in  a  condition  to  demonstrate  the  activity  and 
the  mode  of  operation  of  that  metaphysical 
potency.  But  Darwin's  theory  also  leaves  un- 
explained "what  are  really  chief  and  cardinal 
points,"  and  must  in  addition  leave  uncompre- 
hended  that  "special"  movement  as  the  first 
cause  of  the  chemical  organic  combinations. 

To  this  theory  there  clings  quite  enough  be- 
yond comprehension  and  beyond  explication. 
If  each  and  every  thing  which  we  can  neither 
comprehend  nor  explain  be  a  miracle,  then  are 
we,  in  spite  of  all  that  has  been  attained  by  the 
investigation  of  nature,  still  compassed  by  down- 
right miracles.  Or  is  Strauss,  perhaps,  able  to 
tell  us  how  the  force  of  gravitation  can  put 


ORIGIN   OF  SPECIES.  123 

bodies  into  motion  at  a  distance  of  thousands 
and  thousands  of  miles? — a  fact,  which  as  is 
well  known,  the  illustrious  Newton  pronounced 
as  beyond  the  power  of  imagination.  Or  does 
Strauss,  perchance,  know"  how  to  give  us  a 
statement  "as  to  the  cause  of  the  diversity  of 
"the  chemical  elements,  the  nature  of  the  force 
"w^hich  occasions  the  chemical  combinations, 
"the  law^s  which  control  the  chemical  metamor- 
"phoses,"  things  of  which  Kekule*  says,  "our 
"chemistry  possesses  no  sort  of  exact  knowl- 
"edge.^'  Can  he  bring  within  our  grasp  the 
mode  in  which  light  (the  luminiferous  force) 
sets  the  ethereal  atoms  into  transversal  undula- 
tions, and  how  this  movement  transmits  itself 
in  exactly  the  opposite  direction  in  longitudinal 
undulation,  albeit  physics,  as  Eisenlohr  con- 
fesses, "can  furnish  nothing  certain  in  regard 
"to  the  causes  of  the  wave-movement  of  the 
"ether  effected  by  the  surface  of  the  sun  and  of 
"the  fixed  stars."  Or  is  he,  perchance,  able  to 
explain  the  extremely  diverse  operations  of  elec- 
tricity, which  Eisenlohr  styles,  "the  unknown 
"cause  of  a  vast  multitude  of  phenomena.'^ 
Especially  is  Strauss  at  all  prepared  to  explain 
the  law  of  inductive  electricity;  to  wit,  "that 

^  Lehrbuch  der  Organischen  Chemie,  p.  95. 


124     STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

"  the  induced  stream,  on  approximation  to  the 
"primary  stream,  shows  a  tendency  opposite 
"to  it,  but  on  being  removed  from  the  pri- 
"mary  stream  assumes  the  same  direction  with 
"it?"  These  are  but  a  few  of  the  unanswered 
questions,  of  the  unexplained  and  uncompre- 
hended  facts  in  the  sphere  of  the  natural  sci- 
ences. If  Strauss  be  not  able  to  solve  them, 
he  is  bound  to  confess  that  on  the  first  point, 
even  that  "happier  aftertime'^  has  exceedingly 
little  prospect  of  "getting  rid  of"  miracle,  as 
he  uses  the  word. 

After  this  allusion,  in  passing,  to  the  su- 
premest  benefactor  of  humanity,  Strauss  pre- 
sents us  wnth  a  very  popular,  excessively  super- 
ficial delineation  or  description  of  the  Darwinian 
theory,  without  ever  mentioning,  to  say  nothing 
of  attempting  to  answer,  the  many  and  w^eighty 
objections  w^hich  have  been  raised  against  it, 
even  by  w^riters  of  high  authority  in  the  natu- 
ral sciences.  He  might  have  found  these  in 
Huber's  work.*  This  is  not  the  place  to  esti- 
mate the  weight  of  these  objections.  We  pro- 
pose no  more  than  to  point  out  the  utterly  un- 
critical course  pursued  by  the  renowned  critic. 


J.  Huber:  Die  Lehre  Darwin's  &c.     MUnchen,  1873. 


MAN  AND  THE  ANIMALS.  125 

He  accepts  the  Darwinian  doctrine  with  childlike 
trust.  He  believes  in  it  in  spite  of  the  con- 
siderations of  various  kinds,  the  grounds  of 
doubt,  the  confutations  which  rise  against  it. 
He  does  the  very  thing  which  he  charges  on  the 
"devout  believers,'^  whom  he  so  despises  and 
assails.  This  is  the  way  they  treat  his  critical 
objections  and  assaults.  He  believes  in  Dar- 
win's doctrine  partly  on  authority,  partly  be- 
cause it  suits  his  personal  opinions  and  views! 


xvni. 

THE  APE  AND  MAN.      MAN  AND   THE  ANIMALS,  THEIR 
AFFINITIES  AND  DISTINCTIONS. 

From  the  theory  of  descendence  it  inevitably 
results,  according  to  Strauss,  that  man  is  de- 
rived from  the  ape,  if  not  from  a  species  now 
existing,  yet  from  a  pretended  species  which 
has  become  extinct.  In  a  popular  treatment  of 
the  subject  he  presents  the  grounds  for  this  in- 
disputably logical  inference  from  the  theory. 
He  launches  out  into  testimonies  for  the  great 
intellectual  endowments  of  the  animals,  or  at 
least  of  particular  kinds  of  animals.  He  con- 
curs also  with  Darwin  in  the  opinion  that  in 
the  higher  animals  "the  beginnings  of  moral 


126    STRAUSS  AS   A  PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKEK. 

feeling""^  reveal  themselves.  ITot  only  are  the 
instincts  of  animals  which  direct  themselves 
"to  the  care  of  their  young,  the  anxiety,  toil 
"  and  sacrifice  through  which  they  pass  for  their 
"young,''  to  be  looked  upon  as  "revealing  a 
tendency  to  the  higher  moral  faculties/'  but  "a 
"sort  of  feeling  of  honor  and  of  conscience,  is 
"scarcely  to  be  mistaken  in  the  nobler  horses 
"  and  dogs  which  have  been  well  cared  for."  He 
adds,  indeed,  that  the  conscience  of  a  dog  "is 
"not  entirely  without  justice  referred  to  the 
"rod,"  but,  he  asks,  "  whether  the  case  is  very 
"different  with  the  rougher  class  of  men?" 
That  means  that  the  human  conscience,  and 
consequently  human  morality,  is  to  be  referred 
to  the  rod.  For  that  the  earliest  men,  as  they 
descend  from  the  race  of  apes,  must  have  been 
not  merely  "rough,"  but  excessively  rough,  is 
indubitably  certain,  inasmuch  as  it  is  an  indu- 
bitable consequence  of  the  theory  of  descen- 
dence.  But  apart  from  the  fact  that  this  pre- 
tended conscience  of  the  horse  and  dog  is  to  be 
referred  to  the  rod  and  whip  only^  Strauss 
overlooks  the  fiict,  that  the  whip  must  be  at 
hand,  and  that  there  must  be  somebody  to  ap- 
ply it,  if  the  conscience  is  to  be  brought  into 

*  Sechst.  Aufl.  208. 


MAN   AND   THE   ANIMALS.  127 

being  or  aroused.  Man  uses  the  rod  on  the  dog. 
Who  is  there  to  use  it  on  man?  Another  man, 
of  course.  The  first  man  then  who  employed 
the  rod  to  arouse  a  conscience  in  another  must 
of  necessity  have  possessed  conscience  and 
moral  feeling,  in  and  of  himself,  without  the 
aid  of  the  rod.  The  question  inevitably  arises, 
why  does  one  dog  never  use  the  conscience- 
making  rod  on  another  dog?  Is  it  perhaps 
because  dogs  possess  only  ''a  sort"  of  con- 
science? But  apart  from  the  fact  that  Strauss 
does  not  devote  a  word  of  explanation  as  to 
what  this  "sort,''  be  it  species  or  be  it  variety, 
may  be,  he  must  in  any  case  acknowledge  that 
the  conscience  of  a  dog  or  the  conscience  of  a 
man,  which  is  aroused  and  controlled  by  the 
rod,  is  very  different  not  only  "in  quantity,'^ 
but  in  quality  too,  from  the  conscience  which  is 
self-awakened  and  self-evolved.  His  first  duty 
then  is  to  show  that  the  two  are  nevertheless 
identical  in  principle  and  character.  To  do 
this  he  must  show  that  the  nursing  and  feeding 
of  their  young  by  the  higher  orders  of  animals, 
are  to  be  regarded  as  a  token  of  moral  feeling, 
or  of  the  higher  moral  faculties.  This  is  the 
more  imperative,  as  it  is  well  known  that  as 
soon  as  their  young  are  grown,  as  soon  as,  in 
the   case    of  birds,  the    brood    is   fledged,   not 


128     STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

only  does  the  care  cease  at  once,  but  there  is  a 
change  to  the  very  reverse.  They  drive  away 
their  young,  they  enter  into  the  same  combat 
and  struggles  with  them  as  with  others  for 
food,  all  of  which  furnishes  evidence  of  the 
purely  instinctive  character  of  the  whole.  Until 
Strauss  succeeds  in  doing  this,  we  shall  feel 
justified  in  finding  the  solution  of  his  assertions 
in  that  mingling  and  confounding  of  notions, 
which  clings  to  materialism  like  an  endemic 
sickness,  which  seems  to  attack  every  one  who 
gives  himself  up  to  that  system. 

XIX. 

THE    SOUL. 

The  "  incarnation  "  of  the  ape  leads  the  de- 
fender of  that  view  by  a  very  natural  transition 
to  the  contested  question  concerning  the  soul. 
Strauss  stands  fast  by  the  colors  of  the  new 
faith.  He  denies  without  qualification  any  sort 
of  specific  diflference  between  body  and  soul. 
He  claims,  if  not  to  have  settled  the  question, 
yet  at  least  to  have  broken  the  pathway  to  a 
solution  of  it,  by  proclaiming  the  doctrine  of 
sensualism,  and  referring  all  thinking  to  sensa- 
tion, and  starts  the  question  :  ''If  under  certain 
''  conditions     movement     is    transmuted     into 


THE   SOUL.  129 

'  warmth,  why  may  there  not  be  conditions 
'  under  which  it  is  transmuted  into  sensation  ? 
'  We  have  the  necessary  conditions,  the  appa- 
'  ratus  for  this  in  the  brain  and  nervous  system 
'of  the  higher  animals,  and  in  those  organs, 
'  which  in  the  lower  orders  of  animals  supply 
'their  place.  On  the  one  side  the  nerve  is 
'  touched  and  put  into  motion,  on  the  other 
'  there  is  a  respondent  sensation,  a  perception  ; 
'a  process  of  thinking  springs  up.  And  con- 
'  versely  on  the  way  outward  the  sensation  and 
'  the  thought  set  the  members  of  the  body  in 
'  motion.  Helmholtz  says :  *  In  the  generation 
' '  of  warmth  by  friction  and  concussion  the 
' '  motion  of  the  entire  mass  passes  over  into  a 
' '  motion  of  its  minutest  particles,  and  con- 
' '  versely,  by  the  generation  of  mechanical 
' '  power  by  warmth  the  motion  of  the  minutest 
"particles  passes  over  into  a  motion  of  the 
'' whole  mass. ^  I  ask  then,  is  this  essentially 
'  different  from  the  view  I  am  urging  ?  Is  not 
'  what  I  have  asserted  but  the  sequel  to  the 
'  statement  of  Helmholtz  ?"*  Helmholtz 
himself  would  certainly  answer  this  question 
with  a  decided  No.  Strauss  forgets  that  what 
we  call  warmth  does  not  exist,  physically,  in  in- 

^  P.  206  seq.  Sechst.  Aufl.  211,  212. 


130     STRAUSS   AS   A    PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

organic  nature  at  all.  The  word  designates  a 
distinct  sensation,  which  under  certain  circum- 
stances is  present  and  comes  to  our  conscious- 
ness. Physics  has  demonstrated  that  the  rise 
of  it  is  conditioned  by  distinct  movements  of 
the  ethereal  atoms,  and  in  a  certain  respect  of 
the  ponderable  atoms,  the  "minutest  portions'' 
of  a  mass,  that  is,  it  arises  when  these  move- 
ments meet  nerves  sensible  to  them,  capable  of 
excitation  by  them.  Warmth,  therefore,  pre- 
supposes a  being  capable  of  sensation,  endowed 
with  sensibility.  There  exists  consequently  not 
the  slightest  analogy  between  the  origination  of 
sensation  and  those  phj'sical  movements  which 
pass  from  the  masses  to  their  minutest  parts, 
and  again  from  the  parts  to  the  mass.  The  mi- 
nutest particles  of  air,  when  by  compression  or 
by  the  rays  of  the  sun  they  are  set  into  those 
motions,  have  sensation  of  warmth  just  as  little 
as  the  particles  of  iron  or  silver  in  a  state  of 
fusion  have  it.  For  as  the  illustrious  physiolo- 
gist DoNDERS  observes,  "  The  essential  charac- 
•'  ter  of  all  forms  of  operation,  and  of  the  faculty 
"  of  operation  with  which  we  are  acquainted,  is 
"  motion  and  condition  of  motion,  and  no  man 
"can  shape  to  liimself  a  conception,  how  out  of 
"  motions,  be  they  combined  in  any  manner 
"  they  may,  consciousness  or  2i\\y  psj'chical  ac- 


THE   SOUL.  131 

"  tivity  whatever  can  arise."  Were  it  granted 
also  that  the  nerves,  if  they  are  affected  by  those 
movements,  went  into  a  similar  movement  of 
their  minutest  particles — a  theory  which  is  far 
from  having  been  proven — that  does  not  involve 
any  sensation  of  warmth.  Du  Bois-Reymond 
— an  authority  in  natural  science  to  whom 
Strauss  now  and  then  appeals — puts  the  point 
in  question  in  these  words:  "What  imaginable 
"  connection  is  there,  on  the  one  side,  between 
"  distinct  movements  of  distinct  atoms  in  my 
"brain,  and  on  the  other,  of  facts  primitive  for 
"  me,  incapable  of  further  definition,  beyond  all 
"  possibility  of  denial,  facts  like  these  :  I  feel 
"  pain,  I  feel  pleasure,  I  taste  something  sweet, 
"I  smell  the  aroma  of  a  rose,  I  hear  the  tones 
"  of  the  organ,  I  see  something  red — and  the 
"assurance  just  as  directly  flowing  from  these 
"  facts  :  Therefore  I  am  ?"  Du  Bois-Reymond 
regards  the  question  also  as  unanswerable,  and 
hence  states  the  case  more  amply:  "It  is  just 
"  as  incomprehensible  throughout  and  forever, 
"  that  it  should  not  be  a  matter  of  indifference 
"  to  a  quantity  of  atoms  of  carbon,  hydrogen, 
"  nitrogen,  oxygen  and  others,  how  they  lie  and 
"  move,  how  thej^  once  lay  and  moved,  and  how 
"  they  are  about  to  lie  and  move."  It  is  not 
then  at  consciousness,  not  at  free  will  we  first 


132     STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

reach  "  the  limits  of  our  knowledge  of  nature." 
Those  insurmountable  limits  are  ah-eady  reached 
in  "  the  problem  of  sense-perception."'^  Unless 
Strauss  be  prepared  to  perform  what  Du  Bois- 
E-EYMOND,  in  the  name  of  natural  science,  pro- 
nounces impossible,  unless  he  be  prepared  to  an- 
swer this  question,  unless  he  can  make  it  intel- 
ligible why,  to  a  number  of  atoms  of  carbon, 
hydrogen  and  other  substances,  out  of  which 
the  nerves  in  common  with  all  the  bodily  organs 
consist,  it  should  not  be  indifferent  whether  they 
were  arranged  in  this  or  that  combination — un- 
less Strauss  is  prepared  to  do  all  this,  the  one- 
sided materialism  to  which  he  gives  his  adhesion 
is  an  hypothesis  scientifically  untenable,  as  val- 
ueless scientifically  as  any  other  purely  subjec- 
tive opinion,  as  valueless  as  any  faith  or  any 
superstition  you  may  be  pleased  to  select.  For 
if  it  be  simply  inconceivable  how  sensation  and 
consciousness  can  arise  from  a  mechanical  move- 
ment or  chemical  combination  of  a  number  of 
atoms,  the  mental  law  of  causality  compels  us 
to  suppose  that  there  is  another  cause  for  the 
existence  of  sensation,  not  a  cause  which  ope- 
rates in  a  merely  mechanical  or  chemical  way. 

■^  Ueber  die  Grenzen  des  Naturerkennens,  Yortrag,  etc. , 
Leipzig,  Veil,  1872,  p.  25  seq. 


STRAUSS'S  APPEAL  TO  DU   BOIS  -  REYMOND.    133 

It  compels  us  to  distinguish  the  substances,  the 
atoms  endowed  with  the  power  of  sensation 
from  others  which  are  invested  with  no  more 
than  physical  and  chemical  forces.  The  former 
need  by  no  means  be  purely  immaterial;  they 
may  always  possess  physical  and  chemical  forces 
in  conjunction  with  the  faculty  of  sensation,  and 
may  be  subject  to  the  operation  of  such  forces. 
They  may  beside  differ  very  much  among  each 
other.  Nevertheless,  as  sentient  beings,  they 
stand  over  against  the  insentient  in  well-defined, 
insoluble  antithesis.  With  justice,  therefore,  a 
special  name  has  been  given  them — they  are 
called  "  souls."  Their  actual  existence  contra- 
dicts the  materialistic  hypothesis,  which  acknowl- 
edges nothing  but  physical  and  chemical  forces. 
This  contradiction  is  so  decided  that  none  but 
philosophical  dilettanti,  who  as  a  rule  deal  with 
logic  in  a  very  arbitrary  fashion,  or  men  who 
consciously  or  unconsciously  are  influenced  by 
other  than  purely  philosophical  interests,  can 
still  cling  to  it. 

XX. 

STRAUSS'S   APPEAL  TO  DU  BOIS-REYMOND. 

[In  Strauss's  ''Word  at  the  close,  designed  as 
a  preface  to  the  later  editions  of  his  Old  Faith 

5 


134    STRAUSS  AS  A  PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

and  New  Faith/'^  he  attempts  to  weaken  the 
force  of  the  statement  we  have  quoted  from  I)u 
Bois-Reymond,  adapted  as  it  is  to  shake  the  very 
foundation  of  his  doctrine.  This  he  does  b}^  ap- 
pealing to  Du  Bois-Reymond  himself,  who  does 
expressly  acknowledge,  that,  in  accordance  with 
the  known  principle  of  investigation,  to  give  the 
preference  to  the  simpler  conception  of  the  cause 
of  a  phenomenon,  until  it  be  successfully  con- 
futed, we  shall  constantly  find  our  thinking  drawn 
toward  the  conjecture,  that  if  we  were  only  able 
to  comprehend  the  essential  character  of  matter 
and  force — the  perpetual  incomprehensibleness 
of  which,  according  to  Du  Bois-Reymond,  forms 
the  second,  or  rather  the  first  limit  of  our  knowl- 
edge of  nature — we  might  perhaps  understand 
also,  how  the  substance  which  lies  at  their  base, 
could  under  certain  determinate  conditions  have 
sensations,  desires,  and  thoughts.f  Du  Bois- 
Reymond  certainly  expresses  himself  about  it  in 
this  sense  toward  the  end  of  the  publication  we 
have  cited.  And  it  is  a  matter  that  requires 
no  argument,  that  the  investigator  of  nature, 
though  he  be  unable  to  understand  either  the 

*  Ein  Nachwort  als  Yorwort  zu  den  neuen  Auflagen 
meiner  Schrift :  Der  Alte  und  der  neue  Glaubl.  vierter  Ab- 
druck.     Bonn,  1873. 

f  Quoted  in  Nachw.  als.  Yorw.,  27,  28. 


STRAUSS'S   APPEAL   TO   DU   BOIS  -  RE YMOND.    135 

essential  character  of  matter  and  force  or  the 
cause  and  origin  of  sensation,  has  no  need  to 
resort  to  dogmas  and  philosophemes  about 
them,  but  unconfused  by  them  can  shape  his 
own  judgment  as  to  the  rehitions  between  spirit 
and  matter.  That  is  an  open  question  to  the 
investigator  of  nature  as  it  is  to  everybody 
else.  But  the  first  question  which  arises  is, 
whether  these  ''  views "  be  tenable,  whether 
they  be  more  than  subjective  opinions,  more 
than  mere  ''  dogmas."  But  Strauss  forgets, 
that  Du  Bois-Reymond  not  only  regards  the 
essential  character  of  force  and  matter  as  purely 
incomprehensible,  but  expressly  declares  that 
the  "atomistic  representation"  is  "within  cer- 
tain defined  limits,"  not  only  useful,  but  in 
fact  indispensable  to  the  investigation  of  nature, 
but  that  if  it  be  extended  into  a  general,  un- 
limited theor3%  "it  leads  to  hopeless  contradic- 
tion."* It  is  this  extension,  however,  into  a  gen- 
eral theory,  exclusive  in  its  character,  allowing 
nothing  but  corporeal  atoms,  with  their  ph^'sico- 
chemical  forces,  which  is  the  fundamental  princi- 
ple of  materialism,  or,  to  speak  more  accurately, 
of  that  particular  materialistic  hj^pothesis  on 
which  Strauss  grounds  his  new  faith.  Any 
compend  of  Natural  Science  would  have  shown 

*  Grenze,  etc., p.  9. 


136     STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

him  that  the  atomistic-materialistic  view  of 
nature  is  in  fact  nothing  more  to  the  investi- 
gator of  nature  than  a  "  hypothesis.''  But  every 
hypothesis  is  condemned  as  scientifically  untena- 
ble, just  as  soon  as  it  shows  that  it  is  unable  to 
explain,  or  involves  itself  in  hopeless  contradic- 
tion in  the  attempt  to  explain,  the  phenomena 
which  it  is  framed  and  adopted  to  explain.  This 
is  a  principle  which  the  student  of  science  holds 
as  inviolable,  as  without  it  the  way  is  opened 
to  every  fortuitous  whimsy,  every  arbitrary 
fancy,  in  a  word  to  the  utter  overthrow  of  sci- 
ence. If  Strauss  then  be  unable  to  confute 
these  deliberate  judgments  of  Du  Bois-Reymond, 
and  this  he  has  not  even  attempted  to  do,  he 
must  concede  that  his  new  faith,  based  upon  the 
exclusive  materialistic  hypothesis,  is  destitute  of 
all  scientific  confirmation.  His  defence  shows 
no  more  than  that  those  judgments  are  very  in- 
convenient to  him.  It  creates  the  impression 
of  a  fruitless  struggle  and  solicitude  to  break 
away  from  their  annihilating  results.  It  is  un- 
fortunate for  him  that  the  star,  which  has  led 
him,  already  begins  to  pale,  and  that  the  mate- 
rialistic doctrine  already  shows  that  it  is  a  fall- 
ing star  rather  than  a  true  star.  The  rest  of  his 
"Word  at  the  close"  is  nothing  more  than  a 
defence  of  his  religious  and  theological  views 
against  the  numerous  attacks  made  upon  them 


THE   NOTION   OF   DESIGN.  137 

from  the  most  various  quarters.     We  are  con- 
sequently not  concerned  with  it.] 

XXL 

THE  NOTION  OF  DESIGN,  IN  THE  I.IGHT  OF  NATURAL 
SCIENCE.      PHILOSOPHY   OF  THE  UNCONSCIOUS. 

After  this  long  ramble  through  the  circle  of 
the  theories  of  the  natural  sciences,  Strauss 
comes  back  to  the  investigation  of  the  notion  of 
design,  in  order  that  he  may  weaken  the  teleo- 
logic  argument  for  the  existence  of  God.  Dar- 
win, who  has  opened  the  door  for  the  expulsion 
of  miracle,  "  has  also  removed  from  the  expla- 
"  nation  of  nature  the  notion  of  design,  which 
"  in  the  main  coincides  with  the  notion  of  mira- 
"  cle.''  The  notion  of  design,  to  wit,  as  Strauss 
in  common  with  the  older  teleologists  recog- 
nizes, involves  consciousness  thus  far,  that  a 
spontaneous  activity,  conformable  to  a  design, 
and  yet  without  consciousness,  is  inconceivable. 
To  speak,  therefore,  of  an  activity  involving  a 
final  cause,  setting  before  itself  an  aim,  pursu- 
ing a  plan,  selecting  the  most  fitting  means,  and 
yet  to  deny  consciousness  to  such  an  activity,  is 
simply  self-contradiction.  Strauss,  therefore, 
rejects  the  philosophy  of  the  unconscious,  "  the 
crotchet''  of  E.  von  Hartmann,  which  assumes 
an  unconscious  absolute,  which  as  completely  as 


138     STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

the  conscious  God  of  the  teleological  argument, 
with  clearsighted  wisdom,  works  bj^  plan  and 
choice,  and  determines  all  that  is  embraced 
in  creation  and  the  process  of  the  universe. 
Strauss  justly  remarks  that  this  theory  is  but 
the  change  of  a  word,  from  which  results  the 
ascription  to  a  pretended  unconsciousness,  of 
things  done,  and  of  a  course  of  action,  which 
can  belong  only  to  a  conscious  being.  "If  we 
are  to  suppose,"  he  continues,  "  that  an  Uncon- 
"  scious  has  brought  to  pass  what  appears  to  us 
"in  nature  as  conformable  to  design,  I  must 
"  conceive  of  its  course  of  action  in  the  case, 
"  as  of  that  nature  which  belongs  to  the  Un- 
"  conscious,  that  is,  to  speak  with  Helmholtz, 
"  it  must  have  swayed  as  a  blind  force  of  na- 
"  ture,  and  yet  have  brought  to  pass  something 
"  which  corresponds  with  a  design.  The  newer 
"investigation  of  nature  in  Darwin  has  set  us 
"  above  this  point  of  view."  He  has  shown  that 
the  natural  "  need,"  the  "  struggle  for  exist- 
ence "  has  "gradually  fashioned,  developed,  and 
"  perfected  the  organs  of  living  things,  in  the 
"  way  best  adapted  to  satisfy  the  growing  need, 
"  to  maintain  the  struggle  victoriously.  Thus, 
"  in  the  course  of  the  ages,  ever  higher  and 
"  more  perfect  beings  have  resulted,  more  per- 
"  feet  because  more  highly  endowed  with  the 
"  faculties  necessary  to  carry  on  the  struggle  in 


THE   DOCTEINE   OF   FINAL   CAUSES.  139 

"  every  direction  under  the  most  diverse  condi- 
"  tions  and  relations/'* 


XXII. 

THE  SETTIKa  ASIDE  OF  THE  DOCTRCSrE  OF  FrSTAL 
CAUSES  IN  NATURE  BY  DARWIN. 

Were  we  to  grant  that  the  Darwinian  theory 
is  completely  justified  and  established — which 
it  by  no  means  is — it  yet  seems  to  us  that  the 
notion  of  design  and  miracle,  which  it  puts  out 
at  one  door,  it  lets  in  at  another.  Considered 
simply  as  a  theorj^  it  is,  at  least  in  the  appre- 
hension of  it  which  Strauss  furnishes,  one-sided 
and  inconsistent.  For  if  it  be  nothing  more 
than  the  diverse  forms  of  need  presenting 
themselves  in  the  struggle  for  existence  which 
controls  organization,  gradually  shapes  the  or- 
gans, and  then  produces  new  genera  and  species, 
it  follows  that  under  some  circumstances,  retro- 
gressions may  take  place,  and  have  taken  place 
from  the  higher  to  the  lower.  The  quadruped, 
for  example,  if  a  continent  which  had  once  been 
dry  should  be  covered  by  vast  inundations,  will 
find  himself  confined  to  marshy,  miry  ground, 
and  must  consequently  be  able  to  turn  back,  and 

*  Page  213,  seq.  Sechst.  AuE.  218,  seq. 


140    STRAUSS  AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

must  actually,  under  these  circumstances,  have 
been  turned  back  into  the  reptile.  The  reptile, 
if  it  be  forced  to  live  in  a  comparatively  narrow 
space,  surrounded  by  great  bodies  of  water,  will 
by  degrees,  under  the  pressure  of  hunger,  be 
compelled  to  resume  the  nature  of  the  fish. 
The  theory  of  descendence  can  therefore  logi- 
cally claim  no  more  than  a  vacillation  to  and 
fro,  according  to  circumstances,  between  higher 
and  lower,  between  progression  and  retrogres- 
sion. Darwin  himself  consequently  does  not 
claim  that  there  is  a  law  of  necessary  rise  and 
ultimate  perfection  in  grade.  Nevertheless,  the 
theory,  as  the  facts  adduced  in  its  support 
show,  knows  only  of  the  rise  and  development 
of  species  ever  higher  and  more  perfect — a  pro- 
cess which  terminates  in  the  appearing  of  a  last, 
highest  species,  Man;  and  this  is  the  very  point 
which  Strauss  urges  with  special  earnestness. 
To  this  inconsistency  the  theory  moves  involun- 
tarily. The  facts  of  natural  science  established 
by  palaeontology  compel  it  so  to  move.  But  in  so 
doing  it  falls  helplessly  again  into  the  net  of  tele- 
ology, of  which  it  imagined  it  had  made  a  final 
disposition.  For  first  of  all,  the  primary  lowest 
organisms  must  have  been  so  planned  that  they 
were  not  merely  in  a  general  way  "variable," 
but  so  that   the  variability  of  the   individual 


THE   DOCTRINE   OF   FINAL   CAUSES.  141 

members  should  have  the  definite  tendency  and 
inclination  to  vary  from  what  was  its  original 
general  type,  in  a  manner  adapted  to  its  struggle 
for  existence,  and  consequently  to  put  forth 
organs  fitted  for  and  correspondent  with  the 
needs;  in  a  word,  organs  formed  or  transformed 
in  accordance  with  design.  The  same  princi- 
ple holds  good  in  regard  to  the  entire  series  of 
genera  and  species  which  gradually  comes  forth 
from  the  struggle  for  existence.  Had  mere 
accident  controlled  the  result,  nothing  but  un- 
suitable varieties  might  have  arisen,  or  the  suit- 
able variations  might  have  been  so  insignificant 
in  number  and  importance  that  a  higher  organ- 
ization never  would  have  been  reached.  The 
varieties  must  furthermore  be  so  constituted 
that  they  must  not  only  be  able  permanently  to 
preserve  themselves  without  retrogression,  but 
their  suitably  formed  organs  must  also,  of  them- 
selves, be  developed  and  perfected ;  that  is,  not 
only  their  primary  formation,  but  their  develop- 
ment also,  must  be  in  accordance  with  design. 
But  even  the  external  circumstances  and  rela- 
tions, the  conditions  of  existence  must  have  been 
originally  so  determined,  and  must  in  such  sense 
change  in  the  course  of  time,  that  other  and  yet 
other  needs  for  the  organism  sprang  from  them. 
Otherwise  the  variations  and  new  developments 


142    STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

called  forth  by  the  need  could  neither  take  place 
nor  attain  permanence.  It  is  required,  there- 
fore, that  there  should  intervene  a  series  of  ex- 
ternal conditions,  circumstances  and  relations 
correspondent  with  the  rise  and  preservation  as 
well  as  with  the  sequence  of  the  series  which 
give  themselves  shape.  Were  it  otherwise,  no 
newer  higher  species  could  arise,  and  those 
which  had  arisen  could  not  sustain  themselves. 
Even  in  the  domain  of  Geology,  in  the  sequence 
of  the  stadia  of  the  earth's  development,  there 
can  be  no  domination  of  blind  chance.  Such  a 
view  is  overthrown  not  onl}^  by  the  strength  of 
the  facts,  but  by  the  theory  of  descendence  itself, 
as  a  theory.  For  chance  can  neither  be  in  itself 
a  theory,  nor  be  brought  into  a  theory.  Theo- 
retical or  theorized  chance  is  a  contradiction 
in  the  adjective,  in  no  respects  different  from 
wooden  iron.  If  then  we  are  compelled  to  ac- 
cept a  force  which,  on  the  one  hand,  so  planned 
the  organisms  that  in  correspondence  w^ith  the 
needs  which  from  time  to  time  arose,  they  varied 
themselves,  and  in  higher  and  yet  higher  grades 
transformed,  developed,  and  perfected  them- 
selves, and  if  this  force,  on  the  other  hand,  gave 
such  direction  to  the  external  conditions,  rela- 
tions, and  circumstances,  that  they  went  hand 
in  hand  with  the  formation  and  development  of 


THE   DOCTRINE   OF   FINAL   CAUSES.  143 

the  species,  made  their  changes  in  harmony 
with  them,  and  through  the  entire  processes  co- 
operated subserviently  to  them,  we  think  we 
have  in  this  a  power  whose  activity  involves  a 
final  cause,  an  adaptation  to  design.  For  we 
cannot  escape  the  implicit  adoption  of  the  view 
that  the  formation  of  ever  higher,  more  perfect 
species  was  the  aim  pursued  by  that  force  in  its 
activity,  and  that  in  conformity  with  this  aim 
and  its  ultimate  actualizing,  it  determined  and 
arranged  not  only  the  earliest  germs  of  organic 
life,  but,  never  losing  sight  of  that  aim,  the  ex- 
ternal conditions,  circumstances,  and  relations 
necessary  to  it;  in  a  word,  that  this  force  has  se- 
lected, produced,  and  applied  the  means  adapted 
to  the  attainment  of  its  end.  If,  according  to 
Strauss  himself,  such  an  activity  is  inconceiva- 
ble, unless  it  be  superintended  and  accompanied 
by  a  consciousness,  then  is  the  statement  false 
that  Darwin  has  removed  the  notion  of  design 
from  the  explanation  of  nature,  and  has  reduced 
to  the  swa}'  of  a  "blind  force  of  nature"  what 
appears  to  us  in  nature  as  conformed  to  design. 
Darwin,  in  fact,  even  if  it  be  against  his  wish 
and  knowledge,  has  acknowledged  the  notion 
of  design,  and  has  done  nothing  more  than  trans- 
fer it  from  the  known  end,  the  ultimate  point 
of  the  oro^anic  creation,  to  the  assumed  beo;in- 


144    STKAUSS   AS  A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

iiings,  the  earliest  origin  and  development  of 
that  creation.  [l!^either  Strauss  nor  Darwin 
has  weighed  the  question  whether  the  order  and 
conformity  with  law  which  control  ^organic 
nature  do  not  presuppose  the  conscious,  deliber- 
ate planning  of  a  creative  primitive  force,  and 
yet  I  believe  I  have  clearly  substantiated  this 
position  on  the  basis  of  natural  science.*] 

XXIII. 

"how  SHALL   WE  ORDER  OUR  LIFE?" 

In  spite  of  the  partiality  for  the  "  blind  "  force 
of  nature,  and  the  partiality  it  involves  for  the 
lawless  caprice  of  chance,  Strauss  is  a  decidedly 
ethical  nature,  a  defender  of  the  right  and  of 
the  moral  law,  who,  as  it  were,  contra  nataram, 
in  defiance  of  nature,  merely  as  the  result  of 
his  ardor  in  his  conflict  against  the  orthodox 
theology — a  conflict  originally  warranted  in 
some  particulars — has  become  a  sensualist  and 
materialist.  That  is  made  very  clear  in  the  last 
division  of  his  work,  in  which  he  answers  the 
question,  ''  How  shall  we  order  our  life  ?"  Here 
we  meet  almost  unobjectionable  propositions, 
with  which,  though  under  reservation  and  sepa- 

*  Gott  und  die  Natur,  Zweit.  Auflag.  420,  510  seq. 


"how  SHALL  WE  ORDER  OUR  LIFE?"   145 

rating  them  entirely  from  their  untenable  foun- 
dation, we  accord  in  the  main.  Especially  is 
this  the  case  with  nearly  all  that  he  says  on  the 
political  and  social  questions  which  so  pro- 
foundly agitate  our  time.  But  it  is  just  here 
we  meet  the  grossest  contradictions  to  his  own 
premises.  We  shall  cite  only  a  few  of  the  most 
striking  ones.  "The  laws  of  the  Decalogue," 
he  says,  in  stating  his  views, ''  we  acknov/ledge  to 
"  have  proceeded  from  the  recognized  needs  of 
"  human  societj^  needs  suggested  by  experience, 
"  and  in  this  fact  lies  the  basis  of  their  immutable 
"  obligation  for  us.  Still  in  this  commutation, 
*'  between  an  origin  of  the  Decalogue  in  human 
"  needs  and  an  origin  in  divine  Revelation,  it  is 
"  impossible  wholly  to  avoid  the  feeling  that  we 
"  lose  something.  The  divine  origin  of  the  laws 
"gave  them  sacredness;  our  view  of  their  rise 
"  seems  to  concede  to  them  nothing  more  than 
"  utility,  or  at  most  external  necessity.  There  is 
"  no  way  entirely  to  restore  their  sanctity  except 
"  by  regarding  their  internal  necessity,  their  com- 
"  ing  forth,  not  merely  from  social  need,  but  from 
"  the  very  nature  or  essential  character  of  man."* 
This  means  that  if  it  could  be  shown  that  these 
laws  originated  in  man's  own  nature  we  should 

-  Page  231,  Sechst.  Aufl.  235,  236. 


146     STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

have  to  regard  them  as  possessing  the  same  sanc- 
tity as  if  they  proceeded  from  the  holy  will  of 
God.  But  this  would  involve  the  assumption 
that  if  the  nature  of  man  is  to  be  esteemed  holy, 
sanctit}^  is  in  some  sense  to  be  imputed  to  him. 
But  in  what  sense  does  it  pertain  to  him  ?  And 
if  it  did  pertain  to  him,  it  could  only  have  pro- 
ceeded from  the  social  "  necessity."  For  man 
himself  is  supposed  to  be  through  and  through 
the  creature  of  necessity.  Through  necessity, 
in  the  struggle  for  existence,  man  originally  di- 
verged from  the  race  of  ''  the  primitive  ape.'^ 
It  is  the  necessity  of  social  life,  as  we  were  told, 
which  in  man  in  common  with  the  beasts,  origi- 
nates and  gives  impulse  to  the  moral  feelings, 
the  higher  moral  faculties.  Man's  development 
and  consummation  are  originated,  conditioned, 
and  guided  by  necessity.  How  is  it  possible, 
then,  that  he  should  attain  a  nature  or  a  being, 
w^hich  can  be  anything  more  exalted  than  an  in- 
soluble complex  of  manifold  necessities,  and  of 
the  faculties  adapted  to  satisfy  them  ? 

XXIV. 

THE  PRIMARY  PRHSTCIPLE  OF  MORALITY. 

Strauss  contests  the  correctness  of  Schopen- 
hauer's opinion  that  pity  is  the  sole  spring  of 


THE   PRIMARY   PRINCIPLE   OF   MORALITY.     147 

morality,  and  that  consequently  man  can  have 
no  duties  toward  himself.  In  contesting  this 
view  he  takes  the  case  of  a  young  man  who  has 
been  striving  diligently  and  persistently  to  form 
himself,  morall3\  "Beside  his  intellectual  and 
"  moral  endowments  the  young  man  feels  in 
"himself  other  powers,  powers  in  the  sphere  of 
"  the  senses.  These,  like  the  former,  strive  for 
"active  exercise  and  expansion — reveal,  indeed, 
"  an  energy  and  violence  which  that  higher  im- 
"  pulse  is  not  able  to  command.  If,  neverthe- 
"  less,  he  gives  play  to  these  impulses  of  sense 
"  only  so  far  as  they  do  not  stand  in  the  way  of 
"the  expansion  of  the  higher  powers,  we  are 
"compelled  to  call  it  a  moral  mode  of  acting, 
"  which  cannot  be  deduced  from  pity,  and  which 
"  seems  in  no  respect  the  moral  attitude  of  the 
"  man  to  others,  but  entirely  one  to  himself."* 
But  whence  does  the  young  man  derive  the 
power  to  offer  successful  resistance  to  the  domi- 
nating instincts  of  the  senses?  The  impulses 
are  no  more  than  the  consequence  and  expres- 
sion of  the  necessities;  the  stronger  instinct  cor- 
responds with  the  stronger  necessity  and  con- 
versely. It  would  seem,  therefore,  as  if  a  being 
who  was  purely  the  product  of  necessity,  could 


^  P.  235,  Sechst.  Aiifl.  240. 


148    STRAUSS  AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

only  be  determined  and  guided  in  his  entire 
conduct  by  what  happens  at  the  time  to  be  the 
stronger  instinct.  Or  are  we  after  all  to  sup- 
pose that  this  is  a  freedom  of  will,  a  power  of 
self-determination,  sufficiently  strong  to  impose 
restraint  on  the  diflerent  impulses,  to  hold  them, 
as  it  were,  in  check,  and  to  decide  for  itself  by 
which  of  them  its  activities  shall  be  controlled, 
or  whether  it  shall  be  controlled  by  them  at 
all  ?  Yes,  is  the  reply  of  Strauss,  there  is  such 
a  thing  as  freedom  of  will.  For  "  all  the  moral 
*'  activity  of  man  is  a  self-determining  of  the  in- 
''  dividual  in  accordance  with  the  generic  idea 
''  of  the  race.  First  of  all  to  actualize  this  in 
"himself,  to  shape  and  keep  the  individual  in 
"  conformity  with  the  true  notion  and  destina- 
"  tion  of  humanity,  is  the  sum  and  substance  of 
"  man's  duty  toward  himself.  Effectively  to 
"recognize  and  to  advance,  in  others,  our  race, 
"which  in  itself  is  equal,  is  the  sum  of  our  du- 
"  ties  to  others,  in  which  we  are  to  distinguish 
"  between  the  negative  duty,  which  forbids  us  to 
"  do  anything  in  prejudice  of  the  equal  rights 
"  of  any  one,  and  the  positive  duty  of  aiding 
"  every  one  to  the  extent  of  our  alnlity — in  a 
"  word,  between  the  duties  of  justice  and  the 
"  duties  of  love."^     Man,  then,  not  only  pos- 


*  P.  236,  Sechst.  Aufl.  24L 


THE  PRIMAEY  PRINCIPLE  OF  MORALITY.     149 

sesses  the  faculty  of  self-determination,  but  he 
ought  ''to  determine  himself  in  accordance  with 
the  idea  of  his  race/^  Strauss  proclaims, 
therefore,  without  further  argument,  the  doc- 
trine of  the  freedom  of  the  will,  that  much-con- 
tested doctrine,  which  is  denied  in  downright 
terms,  especially  by  the  whole  body  of  Sensual- 
ists and  Materialists,  which  is  in  general  sym- 
pathy with  his  views.  With  it  he  proclaims  the 
imperative  Shall  of  the  moral  law.  But  apart 
from  every  other  consideration,  such  proclama- 
tions are,  in  their  own  nature,  thoroughly  un- 
scientific. Science  cannot  and  dare  not  allow 
any  man,  not  even  so  distinguished  a  man  as 
Strauss,  to  decide  a  question  of  scientific  con- 
troversy with  a  sic  volo,  sic  jubeo — so  I  will,  so  I 
command.  If  Strauss  desired  to  put  in  a  word 
on  this  point,  he  was  bound  to  take  hold  of  the 
freedom  of  the  will  as  a  problem,  and  to  present 
his  reasons  if  he  felt  himself  compelled  to  affirm 
it.  He  saves  himself  the  trouble  of  doing  any- 
thing of  the  sort.  He  decides  the  question 
without  even  telling  us  how  this  decision  is  to 
be  brought  into  unison  with  his  own  premises 
and  fundamental  views.  And  yet  it  is  a  mani- 
fest contradiction  in  the  adjective  to  impute 
the  faculty  of  self-determination  to  a  being 
"absolutely  dependent'^  on  nature.     It  is  just 


150    STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

as  manifest  a  contradiction  to  take  a  creature  of 
blind  natural  necessity  and  of  its  laws,  a  mech- 
anism built  up  and  artificially  held  together  by 
physical  and  chemical  forces,  the  product  of  the 
development  of  natural  necessities  and  of  the 
instincts  set  in  play  by  them,  and  endow  such 
a  creature  with  an  "  idea  of  its  race,''  and  with 
a  "destination,"  which  the  entire  kind,  and 
every  individual  in  it,  is  "bound  in  duty"  to 
fulfil.  Darwinism,  indeed,  knows  nothing  of 
either  race  or  species;  it  expressly  denies  the 
existence  of  definite  genera  distinguished  by 
permanent  types,  involving  essential  determi- 
nations. The  originated  "living  substances" 
have,  indeed,  according  to  Darwinism,  in  the 
so-called  "  Atavism,"  to  hold  fast  to  the  innate 
bias,  the  parental  type;  but  in  the  "  variability  " 
the  equally  original  adverse  bias  has  to  deviate 
from  this  type,  and  consequently  from  the  idea 
of  the  race.  Both  factors  are  arrayed  against 
each  other  with  entirely  equal  claims,  or  rather 
the  second  factor,  the  impulse  of  variation,  of  in- 
dividualizing, has  on  its  side  the  claim  of  neces- 
sity, the  war-claim  of  the  struggle  for  existence, 
the  supremest  claim  which  Darwinism  recog- 
nizes. If,  then,  we  grant  that  the  individual 
can  make  a  decision  one  way  or  the  other,  why 
should  he  be  bound  in   duty  to  repudiate  his 


THE   PRIMARY   PRINCIPLE   OF   MORALITY.     151 

individuality,  and  sacrifice  his  individual  in- 
stincts, desires,  and  passions  in  favor  of  Atavism  ? 
About  all  such  questions  Strauss  gives  himself 
no  concern.  He  never  even  tells  us  in  what 
his  idea  of  humanity  consists.  He  talks  about 
the  destination  of  man,  but  never  defines  it. 
Not  until  he  has  reached  a  later  point,  and  then 
only,  in  passing,  does  he  make  the  remark  that, 
by  the  destination  of  humanity  nothing  more 
can  be  meant  than  ''the  harmonious  expansion  of 
man's  natural  predispositions  and  capacities."* 
But  he  again  fails  to  see  that  it  still  remains 
necessary  to  show  how  a  being  who  consists  of 
a  physico-chemical  combination  of  atoms,  which 
are  the  original  and  sole  supporters  of  all  his 
natural  predispositions  and  capacities,  can  pos- 
sibly be  in  a  condition,  by  his  actions,  to  con- 
tribute in  the  slightest  measure  to  ''the  harmo- 
"nious  expansion  of  these  capacities  and  pre- 
"  dispositions,"  either  by  restraining  them  or  by 
giving  them  more  strength.  In  the  very  nature 
of  the  case  it  is  clear,  that  if  a  machine  is  not 
so  constructed  that  from  the  very  beginning, 
and  of  necessity,  its  parts  co-work  in  harmony, 
no  one  particular  wheel,  no  single  screw  or 
spring — and  consequently,  by  parity  of  reason. 


*  P.  203,  Sechst.  Aufl.  269. 


152    STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

no  single  part  of  the  brain  or  nervous  system — 
can  produce  the  lacking  harmony,  or  restore  it 
if  it  be  destroyed.  A  machine  with  self-deter- 
mination and  moral  oblio:ation  is  so  manifest  a 
contradiction  in  the  adjective,  that  no  man  who 
is  unwilling  to  talk  of  wooden  iron  will  venture 
to  talk  of  such  a  machine. 


XXV. 

STRAUSS'S    ATTEMPT    TO    SHOW    THAT    HE    DOES    NOT 
HOLD  THAT  THE  UNIYERSE  IS  A  THINO  OF  CHANCE. 

To  all  this  we  may  suppose  Strauss  to  reply 
that  it  is  not  his  view  that  the  universe  is  a 
mere  machine,  a  product  of  blind  chance;  that 
he  has  explicitly  declared  that  nothing  which  we 
perceive  in  and  about  us,  nothing  which  we  and 
others  experience,  is  "an  isolated  fragment,  a 
"wild  chaos  of  atoms  or  accidents,  but  that  all 
"proceeds  according  to  eternal  laws  from  the 
"one  primal  source  of  all  life,  of  all  reason  and 
"all  good;"  that  consequently  reason  is  to  be  im- 
puted to  man,  and  that  his  whole  life,  acts  and 
conduct  should  be  conformed  to  it.  Strauss 
has  undoubtedly  asserted  all  this.*  But  he  has 
nowhere  shown  us  how  this  is  to  be  brought 

^  See  p.  239,  Sechst.  Aufl.  244,  and  in  other  passages. 


THE   UNIVERSE   NOT   A   THING   OF   CHANCE.    153 

into  unison  with  the  ^' blind"  force  of  nature, 
which  not  only  rules  in  the  inorganic  world, 
but  has  brought  forth  the  first  germs  of  life  by 
a  physical  chemical  mingling  of  atoms,  and 
under  the  autocracy  of  blind  necessity  has  de- 
veloped them  into  mankind.  We  are  com- 
pelled to  ask,  therefore,  What  is  this  reason? 
in  what  way  does  it  work?  and  how  is  it  to  be 
distinguished  from  the  rule  of  blind  chance? 
As  we  have  shown  that  the  "delicate,  mild, 
tender,"  cannot,  without  more  proof  than  has 
been  adduced,  be  identified  with  the  good  and 
rational,  there  remains  for  the  reason  which 
rules  in  the  world,  no  other  notion  than  that  of 
necessity  and  conformity  with  law.  On  this 
then  Strauss  ultimately  falls  back  at  the  "con- 
clusion "  of  his  discussions,  where  he  again  has 
occasion  to  speak  of  his  new  faith.  He  there 
says:*  "Our  God  (the  universe)  shows  us  in- 
"deed  that  chance  would  be  an  irrational  ruler 
"  of  the  world,  but  that  necessity,  that  is,  the  con- 
"  catenation  of  causes  in  the  world,  is  reason  it- 
"  self."  Why  the  concatenation  of  causes  in  the 
world  is  coincident  with  reason,  in  what  respect 
this  necessity  is  rational,  we  are  as  remote  from 
learning,  as  we  were  at  the  earlier  proclamation 

*  P.  365,  Sechst.  Aufl   372. 


154    STRAUSS  AS  A   PHILOSOPHICAL  THINKER. 

that  the  rational  is  the  delicate  and  tender,  and 
yet  it  is  manifestly  by  no  means  necessary  that 
all  necessity  as  such,  that  every  concatenation 
of  causes  should  also  be  rational,  that  an  irra- 
tional concatenation  should  be  impossible.  At 
all  events  this  '^necessity"  is  and  remains  a 
"blind"  power  of  nature.  For  that  a  spiritual, 
conscious  power  controls  the  world  and  con- 
catenates the  causes,  the  operative  forces,  is  de- 
nied and  contested  by  Strauss  from  the  begin- 
ning of  his  book  to  the  end  of  it.  The  reason 
for  w^hich  he  argues  distinguishes  itself  from 
chance,  therefore,  by  being  blind  necessity, 
w^hile  chance  is  usually  designated  as  blind 
caprice;  the  latter  might  also,  though  but  for- 
tuitously, have  brought  forth  the  delicate  and 
tender,  beside  the  coarse  and  harsh.  But  what 
does  it  matter  whether  blind  necessity  or  blind 
caprice,  with  reason  or  without  reason,  concate- 
nates the  forces  which  work  in  nature?  If  man 
be  "absolutely  dependent"  on  them  and  their 
concatenation,  we  cannot  speak  of  self-determi- 
nation or  freedom,  of  rational  or  irrational  de- 
cisions of  the  will.  On  the  contrary,  blind 
caprice  might  have  endowed  yet  earlier  the  be- 
ing it  brought  forth  with  a  power  of  capricious 
volition  and  working,  resembling  itself;  the  do- 
minion of  blind  necessity  absolutely  excludes 


NATURE   COMING   TO   SELF  -  RECOGNITION.      155 

everything  suggestive  of  caprice,  freedom,  self- 
determination.  Strauss's  view  therefore  stands 
fast  by  the  wooden  iron  of  a  being  who  is  "ab- 
solutely dependent,"  and  yet "  self-determining.'^ 

XXVI. 

NATURE  COMINO  TO  SELF-RECOGNITION. 

But  Strauss  goes  yet  further.  In  what  fol- 
lows he  not  only  ascribes  reason  to  this  blindly 
working  necessity,  but  also  attributes  to  it  will, 
and  that,  too,  a  will  to  recognize  itself!  He  be- 
gins with  citing  a  judgment  expressed  by  Moriz 
Wagner,  that  "  the  most  important  general  re- 
"  suit  revealed  to  us  by  comparative  geology 
"and  palaeontology  is  the  great  law  of  progress 
"  which  rules  in  nature.  From  the  most  ancient 
"  eras  of  the  history  of  the  earth,  which  have 
''  left  traces  of  organic  life,  down  to  creation  as 
"it  is  at  present,  this  steady  progress  in  the  ap- 
"  pearing  of  more  highly  organized  beings  than 
"  those  of  the  past  is  a  fact  firmly  established  by 
"  experience  ;  and  this  fact  is  perhaps  the  most 
"  consolatory  of  all  the  truths  which  science  has 
"  ever  attained."  Strauss  then  goes  on  to  say: 
"In  this  ascending  movement  of  life  man  also 
"is  embraced,  and  in  such  a  way  that  in  him 
"the  organic  plastic  force  on  our  planet  has 


156    STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL,  THINKER. 

"  reached  its  climax.  As  it  cannot  go  further, 
"  cannot  go  beyond  itself,  it  will  enter  into 
''  itself.  Hegel's  expression — reflecting  self  in 
"self — was  a  thoroughly  good  one.  In  the 
"animal,  nature  had  a  sensation  of  herself :  but 
"  she  w^ills  also  to  have  recognition  of  herself.""^ 
An  astounding  declaration  !  Blindly  working 
unconscious  nature,  with  her  Reason  destitute  of 
personality  and  consciousness,  unable  to  go 
further,  to  go  beyond  herself,  enters  into  herself, 
in  order  to  attain  self-recognition,  and  by  this 
means  to  reach  at  last  consciousness  and  self- 
knowledge  !  But  how  does  nature  come  to  take 
such  an  extraordinary  fancy  ?  What  is  to  pre- 
vent her  going  "  further"  beyond  herself,  inas- 
much as  the  great  law  of  progress  proves  that 
she  is  quite  able  to  go  "  beyond  herself?"  And 
above  all — this  boundless  plurality  of  atoms  of 
w^hich  nature  consists,  and  in  the  unceasing  al- 
ternation of  the  combinations  and  separations 
of  which  she  produces  and  reproduces  herself — 
how  does  it  come  to  pass  that  it  "  enters  into  it- 
self, to  reflect  itself  in  itself?"  Can  an  atom 
of  hydrogen,  oxygen,  or  carbon,  or  any  mass  of 
them,  combine  them  as  you  will,  reflect  itself  in 
itself?    Is  not  this  reflection  in  itself  an  activity 

*  P.  240,  Sechst.  Aufl.  244,  245. 


KATURE  COMING  TO  SELF  -  RECOGNITION.    157 

which  can  be  put  forth  only  by  a  being  with 
soul,  or  intellect,  a  being  bearing  a  "  Self"  in 
itself?  Strauss,  as  we  have  seen,  has  pro- 
nounced thoroughly  unnatural  a  self-conscious 
rule  of  nature,  acting  in  accordance  with  plan 
and  design,  and  has  lauded  Darwin  as  the 
greatest  benefactor  of  mankind,  for  setting  aside 
forever  the  notion  of  design  in  this  sense.  And 
now  we  have  nature  creating  man,  and  in  him 
reflecting  herself  in  herself,  so  that  in  him  she 
may  recognize  herself!  But  if  JSTature  ever 
adopted  this  unnatural  determination,  and  if 
she  really  had  the  power  of  creating  man,  in 
order  to  execute  her  will  through  him,  in  his 
recognition  of  Self  and  of  Nature,  would  it  not 
have  been  more  accordant  with  her  design,  as 
well  as  a  shorter  and  simpler  way,  instead  of 
making  this  wide  circuit,  to  have  reflected  her- 
self at  once  in  herself,  and  thus  have  reached 
the  desired  self-recognition  at  the  outstart  ?  For 
what  good  would  she  derive  from  this  trailing 
self-recognition,  embracing  as  it  would  her 
doing  and  her  working  only  when  it  was  too 
late — after  everything  was  finished  ?  Is  not 
this  style  of  proceeding  irrational  ?  And  this 
blindly  swaying  Nature,  which  knows  nothing 
and  recognizes  nothing,  and  yet  is  striving  after 


158    STRAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

self-recognition,  does  it  not  come  again  into  the 
category  of  the  wooden  iron  ? 


XXVII. 

STRAUSS' S  DIRECT  CONTRADICTION  OF  HIMSELF. 

Strauss  has  so  little  dread  of  the  contradic- 
tory, that  not  satisfied  with  the  indirect  and  im- 
plicit, he  involves  himself  in  the  most  direct 
and  express  self-contradictions.  Thus,  for  ex- 
ample, we  first  find  him  teaching  us  that  nature, 
after  her  organic  plastic  force  has  reached,  in 
man,  its  climax,  "  could  go  no  further,  beyond 
herself,^'  and  consequently  entered  into  herself. 
But  on  the  next  page  he  asserts*  that  "in  man 
"  nature  has  not  merely  in  a  general  way  willed 
"  upwards,  but  has  willed  out  beyond  herself; 
"  man,  therefore,  should  not  only  not  relapse 
"  into  the  animal,  he  should  be  more,  he  should 
"  be  something  better."  Nature,  consequently, 
though  she  could  not  go  further,  beyond  herself, 
has  at  least  loilled  out  beyond  herself.  In  fact, 
she  has  not  merely  willed  it,  but  has  made  the 
impossible  possible.     For  man  exists,  and  he 


*  P.  241,  Sechst.  Aufl.  246. 


STRAUSS^S   CONTRADICTION   OF   HIMSELF.      159 

not  only  "  should  ^'  and  "  can  "  be  more  than  a 
mere  animal  over  again,  but  the  man  of  moral 
standing  and  moral  conduct  is  more.  It  is  true 
he  cannot  totally  avoid  "the  rough,  hard  strug- 
gle for  existence  "  which  in  the  animal  kingdom 
had  already  had  such  an  abundant  sway:  "So 
"far  he  is  still  a  being  of  nature,  but  he  ought 
"  to  know  how  to  ennoble  and  soften  the  strug- 
"gle  in  accordance  with  the  measure  of  his 
"higher  faculties.^^  Man  is  consequently  no 
longer  a  mere  "being  of  nature,"  he  has  "high- 
er" faculties,  in  the  harmonious  expansion  of 
which,  and  by  the  embodiment  of  which  in  his 
actions,  he  exalts  h\mse]{  above  nature.  Nature 
has  then,  in  fact,  succeeded  in  finally  passing 
out  beyond  herself;  she  has  succeeded  in  get- 
ting loose  from  herself,  in  reaching  out  beyond 
herself,  beyond  her  own  measure,  her  own 
strength,  her  own  essential  nature.  She  has 
succeeded,  consequently,  in  becoming  super- 
natural.  In  brief,  she  has  brought  to  a  happy 
issue  the  seemingly  impossible  feat  of  leaping 
away  from  herself.  She  has  jumped  out  of  her 
skin  !  If  she  be  capable  of  such  performances, 
we  no  longer  wonder  that  she  is  capable  of  con- 
tradicting herself,  and  that  she  cannot  only  will 
and  do  contradictory  things,  but  is  able  to  think 
them. 


160      STEAUSS   AS   A   PHILOSOPHICAL,  THINKER, 


XXVIII. 

STRAUSS'S  IDEAL  STRIVIKGS.      HIS  RECOGNITION 
OF   MYSTERY. 

After  man  has  been  thus  hypostatized  into  a 
being  half  natural,  half  supernatural,  or  a  being 
"yet"  natural,  though  supernatural,  we  need 
scarcely  wonder  longer  that  Strauss  speaks  of 
"ideal  strivings,""^  that  he  maintains  that  by 
"the  giving  of  the  higher  position  to  the  indi- 
"vidual  with  his  material  necessities  and  de- 
"mands,  the  loftier  interests,  the  interests  of 
"the  spirit  are  imperilled, "f  and  that  he  de- 
cidedly disapproves  of  "the  direction  which  by 
"pre-eminence  both  science  and  education  take 
"in  America  toward  the  exact  and  practical, 
"the  serviceable  and  the  utilitarian."  In  his 
charming  zeal  for  science  and  art  he  forgets  that 
for  Darwinists  and  Alaterialists  there  can  be 
absolutely  no  ideal  strivings,  no  higher  intellec- 
tual "interests"  overbalancing  the  material  ne- 
cessities and  demands,  no  science  which  does 
not  ask  after  the  serviceable  and  the  utilitarian. 
His  forgetfulness  indeed  extends  so  far  that  in 
defending  the  monarchial  constitution  against 

^  P.  259. 

t  P.  265,  SecLst.  Aufl.  270,  271. 


STRAUSS'S   IDEAL   STRIVINGS.  161 

the  republicans,  he  enunciates  the  proposition : 
''Every  mystery  seems  absurd,  and  yet  there  is 
''  nothing  profound,  neither  life,  nor  art,  nor 
''state,  without  mystery."  We  attach  great 
value  to  such  instances  of  self-forgetfulness  on 
the  part  of  Strauss  as  a  man,  but  considering 
them  as  the  words  of  Strauss  the  philosophical 
thinker,  the  harbinger  of  the  faith  of  the  future, 
we  cannot  allow  them  to  pass  without  remind- 
ing him  that  the  proposition  to  which  he  has 
committed  himself  involves  the  best  defence  of 
religion  in  general,  and  of  Christianity  in  par- 
ticular, and  breaks  the  point  of  his  arguments 
against  the  old  faith.  If  there  be  nothing  pro- 
found without  mystery,  it  is  difficult  to  see  why 
religion,  the  profoundest  thing  to  which  man 
is  able  to  attain,  and  especially  the  Christian 
religion,  should  be  made  exceptions,  and  the 
mystery  which  surrounds  them  be  urged  to 
their  disadvantage,  and  made  a  reason  for  their 
extirpation.  Even  the  God  of  the  new  faith, 
the  Universe,  as  the  primal  source  of  all  reason 
and  of  all  good,  still  bears  in  its  bosom,  as  we 
have  shown,  very  much  that  is  mysterious,  un- 
explained, and  uncomprehended.  But  should 
Strauss  propose  to  distinguish  between  mystery 
and  mystery,  to  grant  one  kind  and  repudiate 
another,  he  must  be  able  to  furnish  a  safe  cri- 


162      STRAUSS   AS  A   PHILOSOPHICAL   THINKER. 

terion  for  the  separation  of  the  true  mystery 
from  the  false  one.  Or  are  we  to  suppose  that 
there  are  grades  of  the  mysterious,  so  that  when 
it  passes  beyond  a  certain  measure  it  is  no  longer 
to  be  tolerated?  This  does  not  seem  to  be 
Strauss's  view.  For  the  last  bound  of  all  the 
mystical  is  the  contradictory,  and  it  is  this  pre- 
cise bound  beyond  which,  as  we  have  seen, 
Strauss  passes  only  too  often. 

XXIX. 

CONCLUSION.      THE  NEW  PHILOSOPHY. 

The  two  "Supplements"  which  Strauss  has 
added,  bearing  the  titles,  "  Our  Great  Poets" 
and  "  Our  Great  Musicians,"  do  not  fall  within 
the  province  of  this  notice.  We  do  not  propose, 
in  the  slightest  degree,  to  disturb  him  in  his 
sesthetic  enjoyment,  which  to  him  supplies  pre- 
eminently the  place  of  religious  edification  ;  we 
are  not  going  to  call  into  doubt  his  high  aesthetic 
culture;  we  see  no  reason  for  depreciating  his 
aesthetic  judgment,  which,  indeed,  we  consider 
entirely  sound,  and  which  furnishes  new  evi- 
dence of  his  profoundly  ethical  nature.  Still 
even  here  it  is  once  more  wholly  incomprehen- 
sible how,  in  pure  beauty,  that  thoroughly  use- 
less, unserviceable  thing,  the  Darwinian  man,  can 


CONCLUSION  —  THE   NEW   PHILOSOPHY.      163 

find  such  a  cordial,  inspirino;  delight !  Nor  shall 
we  go  on  to  demonstrate — a  thing  very  easy  to  do 
— that  the  ''compensation'^  which  the  new  re- 
ligion pretends  to  furnish  for  the  vanished  con- 
solations of  the  old  religion,  for  the  assurance  of 
reconciliation  with  God,  for  faith  in  Providence, 
for  the  hope  of  a  loftier  and  better  being,  the 
compensation  which  Strauss*  proflers  us  at  the 
close  of  his  book  is  in  truth  no  compensation  at 
all.  We  are  concerned  here,  not  with  Strauss 
as  critic,  either  sesthetical  or  theological,  not  with 
Strauss  as  dogmatician,  or  as  a  teacher  of  re- 
ligion, but  simply  with  Strauss  as  a  philosophical 
thinker.  And  of  Strauss  in  that  aspect  we  be- 
lieve we  have  sufficiently  shown  that  his  new 
philosophy,  for  even  it  is  new  as  contrasted  with 
the  philosophy  of  his  earlier  view  of  the  world, 
is  no  philosophy  at  all,  inasmuch  as  it  is  the  per- 
sistent carrying  through  of  a  renunciation  of 
all  logic. 

^  P.  364  seq.  Secbst.  Aufl.  370  seq. 


INDEX 


Adam,  46 
Agassiz,  16,  51 
America,  38,  51,  160 
Animals,  125 
Ape,  45,  46,  125,  128 
Aristotle,  15,  22,  51 
Atavism,  150 
Atheism,  50,  56,  78 
Atoms,  131 


Baader,  49 
Bad,  103 
Baer,  von,  52 
Barnard,  53,  54 
Beyschlag,  40 
Biela's  comet,  113 
Bismarck,  58,  59 
Bohner,  31 
Bronn,  53 
BUchner,  31,  54 


Carriere,  36,48 
Carus,  53 
Casualist,  102 
Causality,  81-84 

notion  and  mental  law  of,  87 
Chance,  103 
Child,  81 
Christ,  50 
Christianity,  45 
Christians,  43,  78 
Clausius,  52 
Comets,  113 
Comte,  19 


Conscience,  126 

Contradictions  in  the  adjective, 

89,  93,  108,  111,  142 
Cuvier,  51 
Czolbe,  53 


Darwin,  16,  90, 120-123, 137.138, 
143,  157 

Darwinian  theory,  Darwinism, 
24,  45,  120,  122,  125,  139-143, 
150,  162 

Des  Cartes,  22 

Descendence,  125 
I  Diderot,  21,  46 
i  Discovery,  100 
I  Discussions,  31 
I  r>og,  126 

I  Donders,  52,  56,  130 
I  Dove,  37,  42 

!  Du  Bois-Reymond,  52,    56,   131, 
I      133-136 


Earth,  110 

Eisenlohr,  51,  123,  124 
Eleatics,  109 
Encke's  comet,  114 
Epictetus,  41 
Epicureans,  94 
Erdmann,  27 


Fahri,  31 

Faith,  the  new,  33,  34,  74,  98 

Fear.  80-83 


6 


166 


INDEX. 


Fechner,  52 

Feuerbach,  31,  41.  42,  93 

Fichte,  1,  4,  22,  31,  37,  40,  48, 

49,  71 
Finite,  111 
Freedom,  105 
Frenzel,  37,  40,  45 
Frohschammer,  31,  37,  47 


Generatio  sequivoca,  116 
Goethe,  58,  60,  61 
Good,  104 
Gravitation,  123 
Greeks,  84 


Haeckel,  53 

Hartmann,  von,  41,  106,  137 

Hausrath,  37,  41 

Hegel,  22,  49,  71 

Helmholtz,  16,  22,  52,  129 

Herbart,  49 

Huber,  36,  49,  124 

Humboldt,  16,  58 

Hume,  41 

Huxley,  54 


Incarnation,  128 
Inconsistency,  49 
Infinite,  108 
Inorganic,  116 
Instincts,  126 
Interest,  points  of,  39 
Introduction,  72 


Jesus,  44,  50,  61 


Kant,  22,41,  51,  52,  113 
Kekule,  123 
Knoodt,  36 
Koelliker,  53 
Krause,  49 


Lamarck,  51 


La  Mettrie,  21 

Laplace,  51,  113 

Lang,  H.,  64 

Lang,  W.,  40 

Lazarus,  49 

Leibnitz,  22 

Lessing,  60 

Lewes,  19 

Liebig,  51 

Life,  116 

Living  substances,  116-120 

Logic,  99,  163 

Lotze,  16,  22,  48,  49,  71 

Luther.  61 

Lyell,  117 


Mariana,  38 

Materialism,    9,   13,   23,   25,  27, 

30,  78,  106,  128 
Materialists,  103,  106 
Mazzini,  63 
Metaphysics,  17 
Metempyrics,  20 
Meyer,  J.  B.,  37 
Michelis,  36,  41 
Miracles,  121 

Mischievous  tendencies,  58 
Moleschott,  31,  47 
Monotheism,  84 
Morality,  105 
Miiller,  J.,  51,  52 
Munchausen,  89 
Mystery,  161 


Nagele,  53 

Natural  theology,  57 

Nature,  159 

New  England,  25 

Newton,  51,  123 

Nippold,  37,  38,  39,  71 


Oken,  51 
Optimism,  107 
Organic,  115 


INDEX, 


167 


Pascal,  22 
People,  62 
Pessimism,  106 
Philosophical  spirit,  18 
Philosophy,  163 
Phillipson,  33,  37,  40,  41 
Physicists,  22 
Planck, 53 

Political  elements,  63 
Polytheism,  84 
Positivism,  19 
Priestcraft,  48 


Rational,  102 

Rauwenhoflf,  38,  39,  58,  64,  66 

Reactionary  tendency,  65 

Reimarus,  51 

Religion,  11,  79-95 

Review.ers,  35 

Ritter,  49 

Rome,  66 


Schaller,  22,  31 

Schelling,  22,  49 

Schleiden,  53 

Schleiermacher,  93 

Scholten,  38,  53 

Schopenhauer,  26,   41,  66,   106, 

147 
Science,  10 
Sensation,  128 
Sensualism,  128 
Smith,  H.  B,  38 
Snell,  53 

Solar  systems,  110 
Soul,  128 
Species,  120 
Sporri,  37,  65 
Sterling,  58 
Strauss,  14,  28,  29,  31,   32,  35, 


69,  73,  75,  79,  89-98,  115-137, 

162 
Stutz,  38 
Supernatural,  12,  149 


Teleology,  90,  137,  139 
Theism,  68 
Tittmann,  31 
Trendlenburg,  49,  71 
Trinity,  100 
Tyndall,  16,  33,  55 


Ulrici,  14.  22,  29,  31,  49,  56,  69, 

70,  92,  113 
Unconscious,  137 
Universal,  98,  153 


Vera,  38 
Vierordt,  53 
Virchow,  116 
Vogt,  31,  41,  45,  47 
Voltaire,  41,  46 
Von  Holbach,  21 


Wagner,  M.,  155 
Wagner,  R.,  51 
Warmth,  129 
"We,"  45,  75,  100 
Weis,  37 
Weisse,  48,  49 
Will,  103 
Wirth,  49 
World,  109 
Wundt,  53 


Ziegler,  38 
Zierngebel,  36 


WORKS  OF  DR.  KRAUTH, 


FOR  SALE  BY  SMITH,  ENGLISH  &  CO. 


Strauss  as  a  Philosophical  Thinker. 

Prom  the  German  of  Ulrici.  With  an  Introduction. 
12mo.     1874, $1.00 

Berkeley's  Principles  of  Human  Knowledge. 

With  Prolegomena  and  Annotations.  8vo.  1874,     $3  50 

The  Conservative  Reformation  and  its  Theology. 

8vo.,pp.  858.    1871, $5.00 

The  Vocabulary  of  Philosophy. 

By  Fleming.  With  an  Introduction,  Chronology,  Bib- 
liographical Index,  Synthetical  Tables,  and  other  Addi- 
tions.   Second  Edition.    12mo.,  pp.  686.    1873,    .     $2.50 

Tholuck's  Commentary  on  John. 

Translated  from  the  Sixth  and  Seventh  Editions.  8vo. 
1872, $3.00 


>0  . 


s  y 


V>V/''^'V'V.V^'>-'*.-'rJ.5T3 


LIBRARY  OF  CONGRESS 


0  013  773  928  8 


mm 


•■Yr*;.V- 


mm 


mm 


::'M 


'v   •■'I 


vv..,;