Skip to main content

Full text of "Structure and function in primitive society, essays and addresses;"

See other formats


STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION 
IN  PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 


STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION 
IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

Essays  and  Addresses 

by 

A.  R.  RADCLIFFE-BROWN 

PROFESSOR  ElOERITUS  OF  OXFORD   UNIVERSITY 

With  a  Foreword  by 
E.  E.  EVANS-PRITCHARD 

PROFESSOR   OF  SOCIAL  ANTHROPOLOGY,   OXFORD  UNIVERSITY 

and 
FRED   EGGAN 

PROFESSOR      OF   ANTHROPOLOGY,   CHICAGO   UNIVERSITY 


THE    FREE    PRESS 

GLENCOE,    ILLINOIS 

1952 


Acknowledgment  for  permission  to  print  the  essays  and 
addresses  in  this  volume  is  hereby  made  to  the  following : 
The  South  African  Association  for  the  Advancement  of 
Science,  the  Iowa  Law  Review,  the  Royal  Anthropological 
Institute,  the  International  African  Institute,  the  Fourth 
Pacific  Science  Congress,  the  Syndics  of  the  Cambridge 
University  Press,  the  American  Anthropological  Association 
and  the  Macmillan  Co.,  New  York. 


COPYRIGHT 

PRINTED    IN   GREAT   BRITAIN   AT 

THE  UNIVERSITY   PRESS 

ABERDEEN 


FOREWORD 

PROFESSOR  Radcliffe-Brown  has  never  had  much  regard 
for  what  he  calls  '  the  odd  things  that  I  have  written 
from  time  to  time  '  ;  his  major  interest  has  been  in  conveying 
ideas  directly  to  students  and  colleagues  by  personal  contacts.  In 
this  he  has  been  eminently  successful.  He  has  taught  social  an- 
thropology at  Cambridge,  London,  Birmingham,  Pretoria, 
Johannesburg,  Cape  Town,  Sydney,  Yenching,  Oxford,  Sao 
Paulo,  Alexandria  and  Grahamstown,  and  in  each  of  these  places 
he  is  remembered  with  affection  and  respect.  The  indebtedness 
of  his  students  has  been  shown  in  two  collections  of  essays — one 
American  and  one  English — w-ritten  in  his  honour.  And  there  has 
hardly  been  a  book  or  article  on  social  anthropology  published 
during  the  last  quarter  of  a  century  which  does  not  illustrate, 
directly  or  indirectly,  his  teaching. 

An  examination  of  the  essays  in  this  volume  will  suggest  that 
his  writings  have  been  just  as  influential  as  his  personal  contacts. 
He  has  not,  considering  that  he  has  been  engaged  in  teaching  and 
research  in  social  anthropology  for  almost  fifty  years,  written 
as  much  as  most  persons  of  his  academic  eminence.  What  he  has 
written,  however,  has  been  faultless.  We  do  not  mean  by  this  that 
we  necessarily  accept  his  methods  or  conclusions  in  detail,  but 
rather  that  the  point  of  view  he  expresses  could  not  have  been 
better  expressed.  Each  of  the  essays  is  perfect  in  conception 
and  in  expression,  and  they  are  tied  together  by  a  consistency 
and  direction  which  is  rare  in  modern  anthropology. 

We  believe  that  the  publication  of  these  essays  will  be  of 
value  for  several  reasons.  In  the  first  place,  they  show  the 
development  of  the  thought  of  a  distinguished  anthropologist 
for  the  last  twenty-five  years,  and  at  the  same  time  illustrate 
some  of  the  more  important  changes  in  the  orientation  of  social 
anthropology,  with  which  Professor  Radcliffe-Brown  was  so 
intimately  associated  during  this  period.  These  essays  have 
also  demonstrated  their  value  in  the  training  of  graduate  students 
in  our  major  centres  for  social  anthropology.  ^The  individual 
papers  are  widely  spread  in   time  and  place,   and   frequently 


&74:0  -0 


VI  stkuctuul:  and  i-unction  in  primitive  society 

difHcult  to  consult.  We  feci  that  in  presenting  this  collection 
of  essays  we  are  not  only  showing  our  esteem  for  Professor 
RaciclifTc-Rrown,  but  arc  also  providing  a  book  which  will  be 
valualilc  to  students  of  social  anthropology  for  a  long  time  to  come. 

E.  E.  EVANS-PRITCHARD. 
FRED  EGGAN. 


CONTENTS 

CHAPTER  PAGE 

— -^  Introduction  i  '^ 

I  The  Mother's  Brother  in  South  Africa  15  ^^ZH 

II  Patrilineal  and  Matrilineal  Succession  32  ^35" 

III  The  Study  of  Kinship  Systems  49  i<^^i 

IV  On  Joking  Relationships  90  i<^^Q 
V  A  Further  Note  on  Joking  Relationships  105  \^M^ 

VI  The  Sociological  Theory  of  Totemism  117  i1i9 

VII  Taboo  133  1^3^ 

VIII  Religion  and  Society  153  i^^-J.r 

IX  On  the  Concept  of  Function  in  Social  Science    178  i35 

X  On  Social  Structure —  188  ' 

XI  Social  Sanctions  205  /?^3 

:I  Primitive  Law  212  i^S3 


INTRODUCTION 

THE  papers  reprinted  here  are  occasional  papers  in  the 
fullest  sense  of  the  term ;  each  of  them  was  written  for  a 
particular  occasion.  They  do,  however,  have  some 
measure  of  unity  as  being  written  from  a  particular  theoretical 
point  of  view. 

What  is  meant  by  a  theory  is  a  scheme  of  interpretation 
which  is  applied,  or  is  thought  to  be  applicable,  to  the  under- 
standing of  phenomena  of  a  certain  class.  A  theory  consists 
of  a  set  of  analytical  concepts,  which  should  be  clearly  defined 
in  their  reference  to  concrete  reality,  and  which  should  be  logically 
connected.  I  propose,  therefore,  by  way  of  introduction  to  these 
miscellaneous  papers,  to  give  definitions  of  certain  concepts  of 
which  I  make  use  for  purposes  of  analysis  of  social  phenomena. 
It  must  be  remembered  that  there  is  very  little  agreement  amongst 
anthropologists  in  the  concepts  and  terms  they  use,  so  that  this 
Introduction  and  the  papers  that  follow  are  to  be  taken  as  an 
exposition  of  one  particular  theory,  not  of  a  commonly  accepted 
theory. 

History  and  Theory 

The  difference  between  the  historical  study  of  social  institutions 
and  the  theoretical  study  can  be  easily  seen  by  comparing  economic 
history  and  theoretical  economics,  or  by  comparing  the  history 
of  law  with  theoretical  jurisprudence.  In  anthropology,  however, 
there  has  been  and  still  is  a  great  deal  of  confusion  which  is  main- 
tained by  discussions  in  which  terms  such  as  'history'  and  'science' 
or  'theory'  are  used  by  disputants  in  very  different  meanings. 
These  confusions  could  be  to  a  considerable  extent  avoided  by 
using  the  recognised  terms  of  logic  and  methodology  and  dis- 
tinguishing between  tdto^raphic_an.d  nomothetic  enquiries. 

•  In  an  idiographic  enquiry  the  purpose  is  to  establish  as 
acceptable  certain  particular  or  factual  propositions  or  statements. 
A  nomothetic  enquiry,  on  the  contrary,  has  for  its  purpose  to 
arrive  at  acceptable  general  propositions]  We  define  the  nature 
of  an  enquiry  by  the  kind  of  conclusionstnat  are  aimed  at. 
I 


2  STRIKTURI-    AND    FUNCTION    IN    PKIMITIVE   SOCIITY 

Ajjstory,  as  usually  understood,  is  the  study  of  records  and 
monuments  for  the  purpose  of  providing  knowledge  about  con- 
ditions and  events  of  the  past,  including  those  investigations  that 
are  concerned  with  the  quite  recent  past.  It  is  clear  that  history 
consists  primarily  of  idiographic  enquiriesi  In  the  last  century 
there  was  a  dispute,  the  famous  Methodenstreit,  as  to  whether 
historians  should  admit  theoretical  considerations  in  their  work 
or  deal  in  generalisations.  A  great  many  historians  have  taken 
the  view  that  nomothetic  enquiries  should  not  be  included  in 
historical  studies,  which  should  be  confined  to  telling  us  what 
happened  and  how  it  happened.  Theoretical  or  nomothetic 
enquiries  should  be  left  to  sociology.  But  there  are  some  writers 
who  think  that  a  historian  may,  or  even  should,  include  theoretical 
interpretations  in  his  account  of  the  past.  Controversy  on  this 
subject,  and  on  the  relation  between  history  and  sociology,  still 
continues  after  sixty  years.  Certainly  there  are  writings  by  his- 
torians which  are  to  be  valued  not  solely  as  idiographic  accounts 
of  the  facts  of  the  past  but  as  containing  theoretical  (nomothetic) 
interpretations  of  those  facts.  The  tradition  in  French  historical 
studies  of  Fustel  de  Coulanges  and  his  followers,  such  as  Gustave 
Glotz,  illustrates  this  kind  of  combination.  Some  modern  writers 
refer J4?  it  as  sociological  history  or  historical  sociolog)'. 

|n_anthropology,  meaning  by  that  the  study  of  what  are 
called  the  primitive  or  backward  peoples,  the  term  ethnography 
applies  to  what  is  specifically  a  mode  of  idiographic  enquiry, 
the  aim  of  which  is-to-^ive  acceptable  accounts  of  such  peoples 
and  their  social  lifei(Ethnography  differs  from  history  in  that 
the  ethnographer  derives  his  knowledge,  or  some  major  part  of 
it,  from  direct  observation  of  or  contact  with  the  people  about 
whom  he  writes,  and  not,  like  the  historian,  from  written  records.] 
Prehistoric  archaeology,  which  is  another  branch  of  anthropology, 
is  clearly  an  idiographic  study,  aimed  at  giving  us  factual  know- 
ledge about  the  prehistoric  past. 

The  theoretical  study  of  social  institutions  in  general  is 
usually  referred  to  as  sociology,  but  as  this  name  can  be  loosely 
used  for  many  different  kinds  of  writings  about  society  we  can 
speak  more  specifically  of  theoretical  or  comparative  sociology. 
When  Frazer  gave  his  Inaugural  Lecture  as  the  first  Professor 
of  Social  Anthropology  in  1908  he  defined  social  anthropology 
as  that  branch  of  sociology  that  deals  with  primitive  societies. 


INTRODUCTION  3 

Certain  confusions  amongst  anthropologists  result  from  the 
failure  to  distinguish  between  historical  explanation  of  institutions 
and  theoretical  understanding.  If  we  ask  why  it  is  that  a  certain 
institution  exists  in  a  particular  society  the  appropriate  answer  is 
a  historical  statement  as  to  its  origin.  To  explain  why  the  United 
States  has  a  political  constitution  with  a  President,  two  Houses 
of  Congress,  a  Cabinet,  a  Supreme  Court,  we  refer  to  the  history 
of  North  America.  This  is  historical  explanation  in  the  proper 
sense  of  the  term.  The  existence  of  an  institution  is  explained  by 
reference  to  a  complex  sequence  of  events  forming  a  causal  chain 
of  which  it  is  a  result. 

The  acceptability  of  a  historical  explanation  depends  on  the 
fullness  and  reliability  of  the  historical  record.  In  the  primitive 
societies  that  are  studied  by  social  anthropology  there  are  no 
historical  records.  We  have  no  knowledge  of  the  development 
of  social  institutions  among  the  Australian  aborigines  for  example. 
Anthropologists,  thinking  of  their  study  as  a  kind  of  historical 
study,  fall  back  on  conjecture  and  imagination,  and  invent 
'pseudo-historical'  or  'pseudo-causal'  explanations.  We  have  had, 
for  example,  innumerable  and  sometimes  conflicting  pseudo- 
historical  accounts  of  the  origin  and  development  of  the  totemic 
institutions  of  the  Australian  aborigines.  In  the  papers  of  this 
volume  mention  is  made  of  certain  pseudo-historical  speculations. 
The  view  taken  here  is  that  such  speculations  are  not  merely 
useless  but  are  worse  than  useless.  This  does  not  in  any  way  imply 
the  rejection  of  historical  explanation  but  quite  the  contrary. 

Comparative  sociology,  of  which  social  anthropology  is  a 
branch,  is  here  conceived  as  a  theoretical  or  nomothetic  study 
of  which  the  aim  is  to  provide  acceptable  generalisations.  The 
theoretical  understanding  of  a  particular  institution  is  its  inter- 
pretation in  the  light  of  such  generalisations. 

Social  Process 

A  first  question  that  must  be  asked  if  we  are  to  formulate 
a  systematic  theory  of  comparative  sociology  is:  ^^at  is  the 
concrete,  observable,  phenomenal  reality  with  which  the  theory 
is  to  be  concerned?  Some  anthropologists  would  say  that  the 
reality  consists  of  'societies'  conceived  as  being  in  some  sense 
or  other  discrete  real  entities.  Others,  however,  describe  the 
reality  that  has  to  be  studied  as  consisting  of  'cultures',  each  of 


4  STRUCTURK   AND    FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

which  is  again  conceived  as  some  kind  of  discrete  entity.  Still 
others  seem  to  think  of  the  subject  as  concerned  with  both 
kinds  of  entities,  'societies'  and  'cultures',  so  that  the  relation  of 
these  then  presents  a  problem.        ^^  ,       , 

My  own  view^  is  that  the  concrete  reality  with  w^hich  the  social 
anthropologist  is  concerned  in  observation,  description,  com- 
parison and  classification,  is  not  any  sort  of  entity  but  a  process, 
the  process  of  social  life.  The  unit  of  investigation  is  the  social 
life  of  some  particular  region  of  the  earth  during  a  certain  period 
of  time.  The  process  itself  consists  of  an  immense  multitude  of 
actions  and  interactions  of  human  beings,  acting  as  individuals  or 
in  combinations  or  groups.  Amidst  the  diversity  of  the  particular 
events  there  are  discoverable  regularities,  so  that  it  is  possible 
to  give  statements  or  descriptions  of  certzin  general  features  of  the 
social  life  of  a  selected  region.  A  statement  of  such  significant 
general  features  of  the  process  of  social  life  constijtutes  a  descrip- 
tion of  what  may  be  called  a  fQzm-afsociah4^e.\iMy  conception 
of  social  anthropology  is  as  the  comparative  theoretical  study  of 
forms  of  social  life  amongst  primitive  peoples. ;  ) 

A  form  of  social  life  amongst  a  certain  collection  of  human 
beings  may  remain  approximately  the  same  over  a  certain  period. 
But  over  a  sufficient  length  of  time  the  form  of  social  life  itself 
undergoes  change  or  modification.  Therefore,  while  w^e  can  regard 
the  events  of  social  life  as  constituting  a  process,  there  is  over  and 
above  this  the  process  of  change  in  the  form  of  social  life.  In  a 
synchronic  description  we  give  an  account  of  a  form  of  social  life 
as  it  exists  at  a  certain  time,  abstracting  as  far  as  possible  from 
changes  that  may  be  taking  place  in  its  features.  A  diachronic 
account,  on  the  other  hand,  is  an  account  of  such  changes  over  a 
periodiJ5n  comparative  sociology  we  have  to  deal  theoretically 
with  the  continuity  of,  and  with  changes  in,  forms  of  social  life. 

X^ulttmL__ 

Anthropologists  use  the  word  'culture'  in  a  number  of 
different  senses.  It  seems  to  me  that  some  of  them  use  it  as 
equivalent  to  what  I  call  a  form  of  social  life.  In  its  ordinary  use 
in  English  'culture',  which  is  much  the  same  idea  as  cultivation, 
refers  to  a  process,  and  we  can  define  it  as  the  process  by  which 
a  person  acquires,  from  contact  with  other  persons  or  from  such 
things  as  books  or  works  of  art,  knowledge,  skill,  ideas,  beliefs, 


INTRODUCTION  5 

tastes,  sentiments.  In  a  particular  society  we_can-jlisiiOArjerxertain 
processes  of  cultural  tradition,  using  the  word  tradition  in  its 
literal  meaning  of  handing  on  or  handing  down.  The  under- 
standing and  use  of  a  language  is  passed  on  by  a  process  of  cultural 
tradition  in  this  sense.  An  Englishman  learns  by  such  a  process 
to  understand  and  use  the  English  language,  but  in  some  sections 
of  the  society  he  may  also  learn  Latin,  or  Greek,  or  French,  or 
Welsh.  In  complex  modern  societies  there  are  a  great  number  of 
separate  cultural  traditions.  By  one  a  person  may  learn  to  be  a 
doctor  or  surgeon,  by  another  he  may  learn  to  be  an  engineer 
or  an  architect.  In  the  simplest  forms  of  social  life  the  number  of 
separate  cultural  traditions  may  be  reduced  to  two,  one  for  men 
and  the  other  for  women. 

If  we  treat  the  social  reality  that  we  are  investigating  as  being 
jigt  an  entity  but  a  process,  then  culture^and  cultural  tradition 
"are  names  for  certain  recognisable  aspects  of  that  process,  -but 
not,  of  course,  the  whole  process.  The  terms  are  convenient 
ways  of  referring  to  certain  aspects  of  human  social  life.  It  is  by 
reason  of  the  existence  of  culture  and  cultural  traditions  that 
human  social  life  differs  very  markedly  from  the  social  life  of 
other  animal  species.  The  transmission  of  learnt  ways  of  thinking, 
feeling  and  acting  constitutes  the  cultural  process,  which  is  a 
specific  feature  of  human  social  life.  It  is,  of  course,  part  of  that 
process  of  interaction  amongst  persons  which  is  here  defined 
as  the  social  process  thought  of  as  the  social  reality.  Continuity 
and  change  in  the  forms  of  social  life  being  the  subjects  of  in- 
vestigation of  comparative  sociology,  the  continuity  of  cultural 
traditions  and  changes  in  those  traditions  are  amongst  the  things 
that  have  to  be  taken  into  account. 

Social  System 

It  was  Montesc[uieu-  who,  in  the  middle  of  the  eighteenth 
century,  laid~tKe  foundations  of  comparative  sociology,  and  in 
doing  so  formulated  and  used  a  conception  that  has  been  and 
can  be  referred  to  by  the  use  of  the  term  social  system.  His  theory, 
which  constituted  what  Comte  later  called  'the  first  law  of  social 
statics',  was  that  in  a  particular  form  of  social  life  there  are  relation^ 
of  interconnection  and  interdependence,  or  what  Comte  called 
relations  oF  soirdai"ity^  amongst  the  various  features.  The  idea 
of  a  natural  or  phenomenal  system  is  that  of  a  set  of  relations 


6  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

amongst  events,  just  as  a  logical  system,  such  as  the  geometry 
of  Euclid,  is  a  set  of  relations  amongst  propositions,  or  an  ethical 
system  a  set  of  relations  amongst  ethical  judgments.  When  one 
speaks  of  the  'banking  system'  of  Great  Britain  this  refers  to  the 
fact  that  there  is  a  considerable  number  of  actions,  interactions 
and  transactions,  sucu  for  example  as  payments  by  means  of  a 
signed  cheque  drawn  on  a  bank,  which  are  so  connected  that 
they  constitute  in  their  totality  a  process  of  which  we  can  make 
an  analytical  description  which  will  show  how  they  are  inter- 
connected and  thus  form  a  system.  We  are  dealing,  of  course,  with 
a  process,  a  complex  part  of  the  total  social  process  of  social  life 
in  Great  Britain. 

I  In  these  essays  I  have  referred  to  'kinship  systems'.  The 
idea  is  that  in  a  given  society  we  can  isolate  conceptually,  if 
not  in  reality,  a  certain  set  of  actions  and  interactions  amongst 
persons  which  are  determined  by  the  relationships  by  kinship  or 
marriage,  and  that  in  a  particular  society  these  are  interconnected 
in  such  a  way  that  we  can  give  a  general  analytical  description 
of  them  as  constituting  a  system.  The  theoretical  significance  of 
this  idea  of  systems  is  that  our  first  step  in  an  attempt  to  under- 
stand a  regular  feature  of  a  form  of  social  life,  such  as  the  use  of 
cheques,  or  the  custom  by  which  a  man  has  to  avoid  social 
contact  with  his  wife's  mother,  is  to  discover  its  place  in  the 
system  of  which  it  is  part?7 

The  theory  of  Montesquieu,  however,  is  what  we  may  call  a 
theory  of  a  total  social  system,  according  to  which  all  the  features 
of  social  life  are  united  into  a  coherent  whole.  As  a  student  of 
jurisprudence  Montesquieu  was  primarily  concerned  with  laws, 
and  he  sought  to  show  that  the  laws  of  a  society  are  connected 
with  the  political  constitution,  the  economic  life,  the  religion, 
the  climate,  the  size  of  the  population,  the  manners  and  customs, 
and  what  he  called  the  general  spirit  {esprit  general) — what  later 
writers  have  called  the  'ethos'  of  the  society.  A  theoretical  law, 
such  as  this  'fundamental  law  of  social  statics',  is  not  the  same 
thing  as  an  empirical  law,  but  is  a  guide  to  investigation.  It 
gives  us  reason  to  think  that  we  can  advance  our  understanding 
of  human  societies  if  we  investigate  systematically  the  inter- 
connections amongst  features  of  social  life. 


INTRODUCTION  7 

Statics  and  Dynamics 

Comte  poTnfed  out  that  in  sociology,  as  in  other  kinds  of 
science,  there  are  two  sets  of  problems,  which  he  called  problems 
of  statics  and  problems  of  dynamics.  In  statics  we  attempt  to 
discover  and  define  conditions  of  existence  or  of  co-existence;  y 
in  dynamics  we  try  to  discover  conditions  of  change.  The  con- 
ditions of  existence  of  molecules  or  of  organisms  are  matters 
of  statics,  and  similarly  the  conditions  of  existence  of  societies, 
social  systems,  or  forms  of  social  life  are  matters  for  social 
statics.  Whereas  the  problems  of  social  dynamics  deal  with 
the  conditions  of  change  of  forms  of  social  life. 

The  basis  of  science  is   systematic  classification.   It  is  the  ] 
first  task  of  social  statics  to  make  some  attempt  to  compare  j 
forms  of  social  life  in  order  to  arrive  at  classifications.  But  forms  \ 
of  social  life  cannot  be  classified  into  species  and  genera  in  the  way 
we  classify  forms  of  organic  life;   the  classification  has  to  be  not  [ 
specific  but  typological,  and  this  is  a  more  complicated  kind  of  1 
investigation.  It  can  only  be  reached  by  means  of  the  establishing 
of  typologies  for  features  of  social  life  or  the  complexes  of  features 
that  are  given  in  partial  social  systems.   Not  only  is  the  task 
complex  but  it  has  been  neglected  in  view  of  the  idea  that  the 
method  of  anthropology  should  be  a  historical  method. 

But  though  the  typological  studies  are  one  important  part 
of  social  statics,  there  is  another  task,  that  of  formulating  general- 
isations about  the  conditions  of  existence  of  social  systems,  or 
of  forms  of  social  life.\The  so-called  first  law  of  social  statics  is  a 
generalisation  affirmingThit  for  any  form  of  social  life  to  persist  or 
continue  the  various  features  must  exhibit  some  kind  and  measure 
of  coherence  or  consistence,  but  this  only  defines  the  problem  of 
social  statics,  which  is  to  investigate  the  nature  of  this  coherence. 

The  study  of  social  dynamics  is  concerned  with  establishing 
generalisations  about  how  social  systems  change.  It  is  a  corollary 
of  the  hypothesis  of  the  systematic  connection  of  features  of  social 
life  that  changes  in  some  features  are  likely  to  produce  changes 
in  other  features.  — - 

Social  Evolution 

/The  tKefiry  of  social  evolution  was  formulated  by  Herbert 
Spencer  as  part  of  his  formulation  of  the  general  theory  of 
evolution.  According  to  that  theory  the  development  of  life  on 


8  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

the  earth  constitutes  a  single  process  to  which  Spencer  applied 
the  term  'evolution'.  The  theory  of  organic  and  super-organic 
(social)  evolution  can  be  reduced  to  two  essential  propositions: 
(i)  Thr.t  both  in  the  development  of  forms  of  organic  life  and  in 
the  development  of  forms  of  human  social  life  there  has  been  a 
process  of  diversification.- by  which  many  different  forms  of 
organic  life  oTof  social  life  have  been  developed  out  of  a  very 
much  smallej  number  of  original  forms.  (2)  That  there  has  been 
a  general  trend  of  development  by  which  more  complex  forms  of 
structure  and  organisation  (organic  or  social)  have  arisen  from 
simpler  forms.  The  acceptance  of  the  theory  of  evolution  only 
requires  the  acceptance  of  these  propositions  as  giving  us  a  scheme 
of  interpretation  to  apply  to  the  study  of  organic  and  social  life. 
But  it  must  be  remembered  that  some  anthropologists  reject  the 
hypothesis  of  evolution.  We  can  give  provisional  acceptance  to 
Spencer's  fundamental  theory,  while  rejecting  the  various  pseudo- 
historical  speculations  which  he  added  to  it,  and  that  acceptance 
gives  us  certain  concepts  which  may  be  useful  as  analytical  tools. 

Adaptation ^ 

ynpiis  is  a  key  concept  of  the  theory  of  evolution.  It  is,  or 
can  be,  applied  both  to  the  study  of  the  forms  of  organic  life 
and  to  the  forms  of  social  life  amongst  human  beings.  K  living 
organism  exists  and  continues  in  existence  only  if  it  is  both 
internally  and  externally  adapted.  The  internal  adaptation 
depends  on  the  adjustment  of  the  various  organs  and  their 
activities,  so  that  the  various  physiological  processes  constitute 
(j  a  continuing  functioning  system  by  which  the  life  of  the  organism 
is  maintained.  The  external  adaptation  is  that  of  the  organism 
to  the  environment  within  which  it  lives.  The  distinction  of 
external  and  internal  adaptation  is  merely  a  way  of  distinguishing 
two  aspects  of  the  adaptational  system  which  is  the  same  for 
organisms  of  a  single  species^ 

When  we  come  to  the  social  life  of  animals  another  feature 
of  adaptation  makes  its  appearance.  The  existence  of  a  colony 
of  bees  depends  on  a  combination  of  the  activities  of  the  in- 
dividual worker  bees  in  the  collection  of  honey  and  pollen,  the 
manufacture  of  wax,  the  building  of  the  cells,  the  tending  of  eggs 
and  larvae  and  the  feeding  of  the  latter,  tha  protection  of  the 
store  of  honey  from  robbers,  the  ventilation  of  the  hive  by  fanning 


INTRODUCTION 


with  their  wings,  the  maintenance  of  temperature  in  the  winter 
by  clustering  together.  Spencer  uses  the  term  'co- operation'  to 
refer  to  this  feature  of  social  life.  Social  life  and  social  adaptation] 
therefore  involve  the  adjustment  of  the  behaviour  of  individual] 
organisms  to  the  requirements  of  the_pri}r<^^«  ^^y  wfiirh  thel 
social  life  continues.  ' 

WEeiPw^rexaTrTtne  a  form  of  social  life  amongst  human  beings 
as  an  adaptational  system  it  is  useful  to  distinguish  three  aspects  , 
of  the  total  system.  There  is  the  way  in  which  the  social  life  is 
adjusted  to  the  physical  environment,  and  we  can,  if  we  wish, 
speak  of  this  as  the  cecological  adaptation.  Secondly,  there  are 
the  institutional  arrangements  by  which  an  orderly  social  life  is 
maintained,  so  that  what  Spencer  calls  co-operation  is  provided 
for  and  conflict  is  restrained  or  regulated.  This  we  might  call, 
if  we  wished,  the  institutional  aspect  of  social  adaptation.  Thirdly, 
there  is  the  social  process  by  which  an  individual  acquires  habits 
and  mental  characteristics  that  fit  him  for  a  place  in  the  social 
life  and  enable  him  to  participate  in  its  activities.  This,  if  we  wish, 
could  be  called  cultural  adaptation,  in  accordance  with  the 
earlier  definition  of  cultural  tradition  as  process.  Wliat  must  be 
emphasised  is  that  these  modes  of  adaptation  are  only  different 
aspects  from  which  the  total  adaptational  system  can  be  looked 
at  for  convenience  of  analysis  and  comparison. 

The  theory  of  social  evolution  therefore  makes  it  a  part  of  our 
scheme  of  interpretation  of  social  systems  to  examine  any  given 
system  as  an  adaptational  system.  The  stability  of  the  system, 
and  therefore  its  continuance  over  a  certain  period,  depends  oq/' 
the  effectiveness  of  the  adaptation. 

Social  Structure 

The  theory  of  evolution  is  one  of  a  trend  of  development  by 
which  more  complex  types  of  structure  come  into  existence  by 
derivation  from  less  complex  ones.  An  address  on  Social  Structure 
is  included  in  this  volume,  but  it  was  delivered  in  war  time  and 
was  printed  in  abbreviated  form,  so  that  it  is  not  as  clear  as  it 
might  be.  When  we  use  the  term  structure  we  are  referring  to  some 
soVt  of  ordered  arrangement  of  parts  or  components.  A  musical 
composition  has  a  structure,  and  so  does  a  sentence.  A  building 
has  a  structure,  so  does  a  molecule  or  an  animal.  The  components 
or  units  of  social  structure  are  persons,  and  a  person  is  a  human 


V 


lO  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

being  considered  not  as  an  organism  but  as  occupying  position 
irya  social  structure. 

J  One  of  the  fundamental  theoretical  problems  of  sociology  is 
that  of  the  nature  of  social  continuity.  (^Continuity  in  forms 
of  social  life  depends  on  structural  continuity,  that  is,  some 
sort  of  continuity  in  the  arrangements  of  persons  in  relation 
to  one  another.~^t  the  present  day  there  is  an  arrangement  of 
persons  into  nations,  and  the  fact  that  for  seventy  years  I  have 
ijelonged  to  the  English  nation,  although  I  have  lived  much  of 
my  life  in  other  countries,  is  a  fact  of  social  structure.  A  nation, 
a  tribe,  a  clan,  a  body  such  as  the  French  Academy,  or  such  as  the 
Roman  Church,  can  continue  in  existence  as  an  arrangement  of 
persons  though  the  personnel,  the  units  of  which  each  is  com- 
posed, changes  from  time  to  time.  There  is  continuity  of  the 
structure,  just  as  a  human  body,  of  which  the  components  are 
molecules,  preserves  a  continuity  of  structure  though  the  actual 
molecules,  of  which  the  body  consists,  are  continually  changing. 
In  the  political  structure  of  the  United  States  there  must  always 
be  a  President;  at  one  time  it  is  Herbert  Hoover,  at  another  time 
Franklin  Roosevelt,  but  the  structure  as  an  arrangement  remains 
continuous. 

V/The  social  relationships,  of  which  the  continuing  network 
constitute  social  structure,  are  not  haphazard  conjunctions  of 
individuals,  but  are  determined  by  the  social  process,  and  any 
relationship  is  one  in  which  the  conduct  of  persons  in  their  inter- 
actions with  each  other  is  controlled  by  norms,  rules  or  patterns. 
So  that  in  any  relationship  within  a  social  structure  a  person 
knows  that  he  is  expected  to  behave  according  to  these  norms  and 
is  justified  in  expecting  that  other  persons  should  do  the  same. 
; -The  established  norms  of  conduct  of  a  particular  form  of  social 
/|life  it  is  usual  to  refer  to  as  institutions.  An  institution  is  an  es- 
vtablished  norm  of  conduct  recognised  as  such  by  a  distinguishable 
^ocial  group  or  class  of  which  therefore  it  is  an  institution.  The 
institutions  refer  to  a  distinguishable  type  or  class  of  social 
relationships  and  interactions.  Thus  in  a  given  locally  defined 
society  we  find  that  there  are  accepted  rules  for  the  way  a  man  is 
expected  to  behave  towards  his  wife  and  children.  The  relation 
of  institutions  to  social  structure  is  therefore  twofold.  On  the  one 
side  there  is  the  social  structure,  such  as  the  family  in  this  instance, 
for  the  constituent  relationships  of  which  the  institutions  provide 


INTRODUCTION  1 1 

the  norms;  on  the  other  there  is  the  group,  the  local  society  in 
this  instance,  in  which  the  norm  is  established  by  the  general 
recognition  of  it  as  defining  proper  behaviour.  Institutions, 
if  that  term  is  used  to  refer  to  the  ordering  by  society  of  the  inter- 
actions of  persons  in  social  relationships,  have  this  double 
connection  with  structure,  with  a  group  or  class  of  which  it  can 
be  said  to  be  an  institution,  and  with  those  relationships  within  the 
structural  system  to  which  the  norms  apply.  In  a  social  system 
there  may  be  institutions  which  set  up  norms  of  behaviour  for  a 
king,  for  judges  in  the  fulfilment  of  the  duties  of  their  office,  for 
policemen,  for  fathers  of  families,  and  so  on,  and  also  norms  of 
behaviour  relating  to  persons  who  come  into  casual  contact  within 
the  social  life. 

A  brief  mention  may  be  made  of  the  term  organisation.  The 
concept  is  clearly  closely  related  to  the  concept  of  social  structure, 
but  it  is  desirable  not  to  treat  the  two  terms  as  synonymous.  A 
convenient  use,  which  does  not  depart  from  common  usage  in 
English,  is  to  define  social  structure  as  an  arrangement  of  persons 
in  institutionally  controlled  or  defined  relationships,  such  as  the 
relationship  of  king  and  subject,  or  that  of  husband  and  wife,  and 
to  use  organisation  as  referring  to  an  arrangement  of  activities. 
The  organisation  of  a  factory  is  the  arrangement  of  the  various 
activities  of  manager,  foremen,  workmen  within  the  total  activity 
of  the  factory.  The  structure  of  a  family  household  of  parents, 
children  and  servants  is  institutionally  controlled.  The  activities 
of  the  various  members  of  the  persons  of  the  household  will 
probably  be  subject  to  some  regular  arrangement,  and  the  or- 
ganisation of  the  life  of  the  household  in  this  sense  may  be  different 
in  different  families  in  the  same  society.  The  structure  of  a  modern 
army  consists,  in  the  first  place,  of  an  arrangement  into  groups — 
regiments,  divisions,  army  corps,  etc.,  and  in  the  second  place  an 
arrangement  into  ranks — generals,  colonels,  majors,  corporals, 
etc.  The  organisation  of  the  army  consists  of  the  arrangement  of 
the  activities  of  its  personnel  whether  in  time  of  peace  or  in  time 
of  war.  Within  an  organisation  each  person  may  be  said  to  have 
a  role.  Thus  we  may  say  that  when  we  are  dealing  with  a  structural 
system  we  are  concerned  with  a  system  of  social  positions,  while 
in  an  organisation  we  deal  with  a  system  of  roles. 


12  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

SocialFunciicm^ — 

The  term  function  has  a  very  great  number  of  different 
meanings  in  different  contexts.  In  mathematics  the  word,  as 
introduced  by  Euler  in  the  eighteenth  century,  refers  to  an 
expression  or  symbol  which  can  be  written  on  paper,  such  as 
'log.  x\  and  has  no  relation  whatever  to  the  same  word  as  used 
in  such  a  science  as  physiology.  In  physiology  the  concept  of 
function  is  of  fundamental  importance  as  enabling  us  to  deal  with 
the  continuing  relation  of  structure  and  process  in  organic  life. 
A  complex  organism,  such  as  a  human  body,  has  a  structure 
as  an  arrangement  of  organs  and  tissues  and  fluids.  Even  an 
organism  that  consists  of  a  single  cell  has  a  structure  as  an  arrange- 
ment of  molecules.  An  organism  also  has  a  life,  and  by  this  we 
refer  to  a  process,  ^he  concept  of  organic  function  is  one  that  is 
used  to  refer  to  the  CDnnection  between  the  structure  of  an  organ- 
ism and  the  life  process  of  that  organisnD  The  processes  that  go 
on  within  a  human  body  while  it  is  living  are  dependent  on  the 
organic  structure.  It  is  the  function  of  the  heart  to  pump  blood 
through  the  body.  The  organic  structure,  as  a  living  structure, 
depends  for  its  continued  existence  on  the  processes  that  make  up 
the  total  life  processes.  If  the  heart  ceases  to  perform  its  function 
the  life  process  comes  to  an  end  and  the  structure  as  a  living 
structure  also  comes  to  an  end.  Thus  process  is  dependent  on 
structure  and  continuity  of  structure  is  dependent  on  process. 

In  reference  to  social  systems  and  their  theoretical  under- 
standing one  way  of  using  the  concept  of  function  is  the  same  as 
its  scientific  use  in  physiology.  It  can  be  used  to  refer  to  the 
interconnection  between  the  social  structure  and  the  process  of 
social  life.  It  is  this  use  of  the  word  function  that  seems  to  me  to 
make  it  a  useful  term  in  comparative  sociology !^he  three  concepts 
of  process,  structure  and  function  are  thus  components  of  a  single 
theory  as  a  scheme  of  interpretation  of  human  social  systems. 
The  three  concepts  are  logically  interconnected,  since  'function' 
is  used  to  refer  to  the  relations  of  process  and  structure.  The  theory 
is  one  that  we  can  apply  to  the  study  both  of  continuity  in  forms 
of  social  life  and  also  to  processes  of  change  in  those  forms. 

If  we  consider  such  a  feature  of  social  life  as  the  punishment 
of  crime,  or  in  other  words  the  application,  by  some  organised 
procedure,  of  penal  sanctions  for  certain  kinds  of  behaviour,  and  • 


INTRODUCTION  1 3 

ask  what  is  its  social  function,  we  have  a  fundamental  problem 
of  comparative  sociology  towards  which  a  first  contribution  was 
made  by  Durkheim  in  his  Division  du  Travail  Social.  A  very  wide 
general  problem  is  posed  when  we  ask  what  is  the  social  function 
of  religion.  As  it  has  been  pointed  out  in  one  of  the  papers  in  this 
volume,  the  study  of  this  problem  requires  the  consideration  of  a 
large  number  of  more  limited  problems,  such  as  that  of  the  social 
function  of  ancestor  worship  in  those  societies  in  which  it  is  found. 
But  in  these  more  limited  investigations,  if  the  theory  here 
outlined  is  accepted,  the  procedure  Kas  to  be  the  examination 
of  the  connection  between  the  structural  features  of  the  social 
life  and  the  corresponding  social  process  as  both  involved  in  a 
continuing  system. 

The  first  paper  in  this  collection  may  serve  to  illustrate  these 
theoretical  ideas.  It  deals  with  an  institution  by  which  a  sister's 
son  is  allowed  privileged  familiarity  in  his  conduct  towards  his 
mother's  brother.  The  custom  is  known  in  tribes  of  North  America 
such  as  the  Winnebago  and  others,  in  peoples  of  Oceania,  such  as 
the  inhabitants  of  Fiji  and  Tonga,  and  in  some  tribes  of  Africa. 
My  own  observations  on  this  institution  were  made  in  Tonga  and 
Fiji,  but  as  the  paper  was  addressed  to  a  South  African  audience 
it  seemed  preferable  to  refer  to  a  single  South  African  example, 
since  a  wider  comparative  discussion  would  have  called  for  a  much 
longer  essay.  The  usual  way  of  dealing  with  this  institution,  both 
in  Oceania  and  in  Africa,  was  to  offer  a  pseudo-historical  ex- 
planation to  the  effect  that  it  was  a  survival  in  a  patrilineal  society 
from  a  former  condition  of  mother-right. 

The  alternative  method  of  dealing  with  the  institution  is  to  look 
for  a  theoretical  understanding  of  it  as  a  part  of  a  kinship  system  of 
a  certain  type,  within  which  it  has  a  discoverable  function.  We 
do  not  yet  have  a  systematic  general  typology  of  kinship  systems, 
for  the  construction  of  such  is  a  laborious  undertaking.  I  have 
indicated  some  partial  and  provisional  results  of  such  an  attempt 
to  determine  types  in  a  recent  publication  in  the  form  of  an 
Introduction  to  a  book  on  African  Systems  of  Kinship  and 
Marriage.  Amongst  the  great  diversity  of  kinship  systems  we  can, 
I  think,  recognise  a  type  of  what  we  may  call  father-right,  and 
another  of  mother-right.  In  both  these  types  the  kinship  structure 
is  based  on  lineages  with  maximum  emphasis  on  lineage  relation- 
ships. In  mother-right  the  lineage  is  matrilineal,  a  child  belonging 


14  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

to  the  lineage  of  the  mother.  Practically  all  the  jural  relations 
of  a  man  are  those  with  his  matrilineal  lineage  and  its  members, 
and  therefore  he  is  largely  dependent  on  his  mother's  brothers,  who 
exercise  authority  and  control  over  him  and  to  whom  he  looks  for 
protection  and  for  inheritance  of  property.  In  a  system  of  father- 
right,  on  the  other  hand,  a  man  is  largely  dependent  on  his 
patrilineal  lineage  and  therefore  on  his  father  and  father's  brothers, 
who  exercise  authority  and  control  over  him,  while  it  is  to  them 
that  he  has  to  look  for  protection  and  for  inheritance.  Father-right 
is  represented  by  the  sysyefn  of  patria  potestas  of  ancient  Rome, 
and  there  are  systems  that  approximate  more  or  less  closely  to  the 
type  to  be  found  in  Africa  and  elsewhere.  We  may  regard  the 
BaThonga  as  so  approximating.  Mother-right  is  represented 
by  the  systems  of  the  Nayar  of  Malabar  and  the  Menangkubau 
Malays,  and  again  there  are  systems  elsewhere  that  approximate 
to  the  type. 

The  point  of  the  paper  on  the  mother's  brother  may  be  said 
to  be  to  contrast  with  the  explanation  by  pseudo-history  the 
interpretation  of  the  institution  to  which  it  refers  as  having  a 
function  in  a  kinship  system  with  a  certain  type  of  structure.  If 
I  were  to  rewrite  the  paper  after  thirty  years  I  should  certainly 
modify  and  expand  it.  But  it  has  been  suggested  to  me  that  the 
paper  may  have  a  certain  minor  historical  interest  in  relation  to 
the  development  of  thought  in  anthropology  and  it  is  therefore 
reprinted  almost  as  it  was  written  with  only  minor  alterations. 

Any  interest  this  volume  may  have  will  probably  be  as  an 
exposition  of  a  theory,  in  the  sense  in  which  the  word  theory  is 
here  used  as  a  scheme  of  interpretation  thought  to  be  applicable 
to  the  understanding  of  a  class  of  phenomena.  The  theory  can 
be  stated  by  means  of  the  three  fundamental  and  connected 
concepts  of  'process',  'structure'  and  'function'.  It  is  derived 
from  such  earlier  writers  as  Montesquieu,  Comte,  Spencer, 
Durkheim  and  thus  belongs  to  a  cultural  tradition  of  two 
hundred  years.  This  introduction  contains  a  reformulation  in 
which  certain  terms  are  used  differently  from  the  way  they  were 
used  in  the  early  papers  here  reprinted.  For  example,  in  the 
earliest  papers  written  twenty  or  more  years  ago  the  word  'culture' 
is  used  in  the  accepted  meaning  of  that  time  as  a  general  term 
for  the  way  of  life,  including  the  way  of  thought,  of  a  particular 
locally  defined  social  group. 


CHAPTER     I 

THE  MOTHER'S  BROTHER  IN  SOUTH  AFRICA  i 

A  MONGST  primitive  peoples  in  many  parts  of  the  world  a 
/\  good  deal  of  importance  is  attached  to  the  relationship  of 
^  jLmother's  brother  and  sister's  son.  In  some  instances,  the 
sister's~^n~has^  certain  special  rights  over  the  property  of  his 
mother's  brother.  At  one  time  it  was  usual  to  regard  these  customs 
as  being  connected  with  matriarchal  institutions,  and  it  was  held 
that  their  presence  in  a  patrilineal  people  could  be  regarded  as 
evidence  that  that  people  had  at  some  time  in  the  past  been  matri- 
lineal.  This  view  is  still  held  by  a  few  anthropologists  and  has 
been  adopted  by  Mr.  Junod  in  his  book  on  the  BaThonga  people 
of  Portuguese  East  Africa.  Referring  to  the  customs  relating  to 
the  behaviour  of  the  mother's  brother  and  the  sister's  son  to  one 
another,  he  says:  'Now,  having  enquired  with  special  care  into  this 
most  curious  feature  of  the  Thonga  system,  I  come  to  the  con- 
clusion that  the  only  possible  explanation  is  that,  in  former  and 
very  remote  times,  our  tribe  has  passed  through  the  matriarchal 
stage.'  (Junod,  The  Life  of  a  South  African  Tribe,  191 3,  Vol.  I, 

p.  253-) 

It  is  with  this  theory  that  I  wish  to  deal  in  this  paper;  but  I 
do  not  propose  to  repeat  or  add  to  the  objections  that  have  been 
raised  against  it  by  various  critics  in  recent  years.  Purely  negative 
criticism  does  not  advance  a  science.  The  only  satisfactory  way 
of  getting  rid  of  an  unsatisfactory  hypothesis  is  to  find  a  better 
one.  I  propose,  therefore,  to  put  before  you  an  alternative  hypo- 
thesis, and  if  I  am  successful,  not  in  proving  my  h3^o- 
thesis,  but  in  showing  that  it  does  give  a  possible  explanation  ot 
the  facts,  I  shall  at  least  have  refuted  the  view  of  Mr.  Junod  that 
the  explanation  he  accepts  is  the  'only  possible'  one. 

For  many  African  tribes  we  have  almost  no  information  about 
customs  of  this  kind.  Not  that  the  customs  do  not  exist,  or 
are  not  important  to  the  natives  themselves,  but  because  the 

^  A  paper  read  before  the  South  African  Association  for  the  Advancement 
of  Science,  9  July  1924,  and  printed  in  South  African  Journal  of  Science, 
Vol.  XXI,  pp.  542-55. 


1 6  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

systematic  and  scientific  study  of  the  natives  of  this  country  has 
as  yet  hardly  begun.  I  shall,  therefore,  have  to  refer  chiefly  to 
the  customs  of  the  BaThonga  as  recorded  by  Mr.  Junod.  These  are 
to  be  found  in  the  first  volume  of  the  work  quoted  above  (pp.  225 
et  seq.,  and  pp.  253  et  seq.).  Some  of  the  more  important  of  them 
may  be  summarised  as  follows: 

1.  The  uterine  nephew  all  through  his  career  is  the  object  of 
special  care  on  the  part  of  his  uncle. 

2.  When  the  nephew  is  sick  the  mother's  brother  sacrifices 
on  his  behalf. 

3.  The  nephew  is  permitted  to  take  many  liberties  with  his 
mother's  brother;  for  example,  he  may  go  to  his  uncle's 
home  and  eat  up  the  food  that  has  been  prepared  for  the 
latter's  meal. 

4.  The  nephew  claims  some  of  the  property  of  his  mother's 
brother  when  the  latter  dies,  and  may  sometimes  claim 
one  of  the  widows. 

5.  When  the  mother's  brother  offers  a  sacrifice  to  liis  ancestors 
the  sister's  son  steals  and  consumes  the  portion  of  meat  or 
beer  offered  to  the  gods. 

It  must  not  be  supposed  that  these  customs  are  peculiar  to 
the  BaThonga.  There  is  evidence  that  similar  customs  may  be 
found  amongst  other  African  tribes,  and  we  know  of  the  existence 
of  similar  customs  amongst  other  peoples  in  various  parts  of  the 
world.  In  South  Africa  itself  customs  of  this  kind  have  been  found 
by  Mrs.  Hoernle  amongst  the  Nama  Hottentots.  The  sister's  son 
may  behave  with  great  freedom  towards  his  mother's  brother,  and 
may  take  any  particularly  fine  beast  from  his  herd  of  cattle,  or  any 
particularly  fine  object  that  he  may  possess.  On  the  contrary,  the 
mother's  brother  may  take  from  his  nephew's  herd  any  beast 
that  is  deformed  or  decrepit,  and  may  take  any  old  and  worn-out 
object  he  may  possess. 

What  is  particularly  interesting  to  me  is  that  in  the  part  of 
Polynesia  that  I  know  best,  that  is,  in  the  Friendly  Islands 
(Tonga)  and  in  Fiji,  we  find  customs  that  show  a  very  close 
resemblance  to  those  of  the  BaThonga.  There,  also,  the  sister's 
son  is  permitted  to  take  many  liberties  with  his  mother's  brother, 
and  to  take  any  of  his  uncle's  possessions  that  he  may  desire.  And 
there  also  we  find  the  custom  that,   w'hen   the  uncle  makes  a 


THE    MOTHER  S   BROTHER    IN    SOUTH    AFRICA  1 7 

sacrifice,  the  sister's  son  takes  away  the  portion  offered  to  the  gods, 
and  may  eat  it.  I  shall,  therefore,  make  occasional  references  to  the 
Toogan  customs  in  the  course  of  this  paper. 

'  These  three  peoples,  the  BaThonga,  the  Nama,  and  the 
Tongans,  have  patrilineaLjor  patriarchal  institutions;  that  is, 
the  children  belong  to  the  social  group  of  the  father,  not  to  that 
of  the  mother;  and  property  is  inherited  in  the  male  line,  passing 
normally  from  a  father  to  his  son^The  view  that  I  am  opposing  is 
that  the  customs  relating  to  the  mother's  brother  can  only  be 
explained  by  supposing  that,  at  some  past  time,  these  peoples 
had  matrilineal  institutions,  such  as  are  found  today  amongst 
other  primitive  peoples,  with  whom  the  children  belong  to 
the  social  group  of  the  mother,  and  property  is  inherited  in  the 
female  line,  passing  from  a  man  to  his  brother  and  to  his 
sister's  sons. 

llt^s  a  mistake  to  suppose  that  we  can  understand  the  insti- 
tutions of  society  by  studying  them  in  isolation  without  regard 
to  other  institutions  with  which  they  coexist  and  with  which  they 
may  be  correlated,  and  I  wish  to  call  attention  to  a  correlation 
that  seems  to  exist  between  customs  relating  to  the  mother's 
brother  and  customs  relating  to  the  father's  sister.  So  far  as 
present  information  goes,  where  we  find  the  mother's  brother 
important  we  also  find  that  the  father's  sister  is  equally  important,  _ 
though  in  a  different  way.  The  custom  of  allowing  the  sister's' 
son  to  take  liberties  with  his  mother's  brother  seems  to  be 
generally  accompanied  with  an  obligation  of  particular  respect 
and  obedience  to  the  father's  sister.-Mr.  Junod  says  little  about 
the  father's  sister  amongst  the  BaThonga.  Speaking  of  a  man's 
behaviour  to  this  relative  (his  rarana)  he  says  simply:  'He  shows 
her  great  respect.  However,  she  is  not  in  any  way  a  mother 
{mamanay  (op.  cit.,  p.  223).  About  the  Nama  Hottentots  we 
have  better  information,  and  there  the  father's  sister  is  the  object 
of  the  very  greatest  respect  on  the  part  of  her  brother's  child. 
In  Tonga  this  custom  is  very  clearly  defined.  A  man's  father's 
sister  is  the  one  relative  above  all  others  whom  he  must  respect 
and  obey.  If  she  selects  a  wife  for  him  he  must  marry  her  without 
even  venturing  to  demur  or  to  voice  any  objection;  and  so  through- 
out his  life,  jjis  fother^^i^teris^sao^^^  her  word  is  his 
law;  and  one  of  the  greatest  offences  of  which  he  could  be  guilty 
would  be  to  show  himself  lacking  in  respect  to  her. 


16  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

Now  this  correlation  (which  is  not  confined,  of  course, 
to  the  three  instances  I  have  mentioned,  but  seems,  as  I  have  said, 
to  be  general)  must  be  taken  into  account  in  any  explanation  of 
the  customs  relating  to  the  mother's  brother,  for  the  correlated 
customs  are,  if  I  am  right,  not  independent  institutions,  but  part 
of  one  system;  and  no  explanation  of  one  part  of  the  system  is 
satisfactory  unless  it  fits  in  with  an  analysis  of  the  system  as 
a  whole. 

,  In  most  primitive  societies  the  social  relations  of  individuals 
ar^r-^ery  largely  regulated  on  the  basis  of  kinship.  This  is  brought 
about  by  the  formation  of  fixed  and  more  or  less  definite  patterns 
of  behaviour  for  each  of  the  recognised  kinds  of  relationship. 
There  is  a  special  pattern  of  behaviour,  for  example,  for  a  son 
towards  his  father,  and  another  for  a  younger  brother  towards 
his  elder  brother.  The  particular  patterns  vary  from  one  society 
to  another;  but  there  are  certain  fundamental  principles  or 
tendencies  which  appear  in  all  societies,  or  in  all  those  of  a 
certain  type.  It  is  these  general  tendencies  that  it  is  the  special 
task  of  social  anthropology  to  discover  and  explamT] 

Once  we  start  tracing  out  relationship  to  any-xonsiderable 
distance  the  number  of  different  kinds  of  relatives  that  it  is 
logically  possible  to  distinguish  is  very  large.  This  difficulty  is 
avoided  in  primitive  society  by  a  system  of  classification,  by 
which  relatives  of  what  might  logically  be  held  to  be  of  different 
kinds  are  classified  into  a  limited  number  of  kinds.  The  principle 
of  classification  that  is  most  commonly  adopted  in  primitive 
society  may  be  stated  as  that  of  the  equivalence  of  brothers.  In 
other  words  if  I  stand  in  a  particular  relation  to  one  man  I  regard 
myself  as  standing  in  the  same  general  kind  of  relation  to  his 
brother;  and  similarly  with  a  woman  and  her  sister.  In  this  way 
the  father's  brother  comes  to  be  regarded  as  a  sort  of  father,  and 
his  sons  are,  therefore,  relatives  of  the  same  kind  as  brothers. 
Similarly,  the  mother's  sister  is  regarded  as  another  mother,  and 
her  children  are  therefore  brothers  and  sisters.  The  system  is  the 
one  to  be  found  amongst  the  Bantu  tribes  of  South  Africa,  and 
amongst  the  Nama  Hottentots,  and  also  in  the  Friendly  Islands. 
By  means  of  this  principle  primitive  societies  are  able  to  arrive 
at  definite  patterns  of  behaviour  towards  uncles  and  aunts  and 
cousins  of  certain  kinds.  A  man's  behaviour  towards  his  father's 
brother  must  be  of  the   same   general  kind  as   his  behaviour 


V 


THE   MOTHER  S  BROTHER   IN   SOUTH   AFRICA  1 9 

towards  his  own  father  and  he  must  behave  to  his  mother's  sister 
according  to  the  same  pattern  as  towards  his  mother.  The  children 
of  his  father's  brother  or  of  the  mother's  sister  must  be  treated 
in  very  much  the  same  way  as  brothers  and  sisters. 

This  principle,  however,  does  not  give  us  immediately  any 
pattern  for  either  the  mother's  brother  or  the  father's  sister.  It 
would  be  possible,  of  course,  to  treat  the  former  as  being  like  a 
father  and  the  latter  as  similar  to  a  mother,  and  this  course  does 
seem  to  have  been  adopted  in  a  few  societies.  A  tendency  in  this 
direction  is  found  in  some  parts  of  Africa  and  in  some  parts  of 
Polynesia.  But  it  is  characteristic  of  societies  in  which  the  classi- 
ficatory  system  of  kinship  is  either  not  fully  developed  or  has 
been  partly  effaced. 

Where  the  classificatory  system  of  kinship  reaches  a  high 
degree  of  development  or  elaboration  another  tendency  makes  its 
appearance:  the  tendency  to  develop  patterns  for  the  mother's 
brother  and  the  father's  sister  by  regarding  the  former  as  a  sort 
of  male  mother  and  the  latter  as  a  sort  of  female  father.  This 
tendency  sometimes  makes  its  appearance  in  language.  Thus, 
in  South  Africa  the  common  term  for  the  mother's  brother  is 
malume  or  umalume,  which  is  a  compound  formed  from  the  stem 
for  'mother' — ma — and  a  suffix  meaning  'male'.  Amongst  the 
BaThonga  the  father's  sister  is  called  rarana,  a  term  which  Mr. 
Junod  explains  as  meaning  'female  father'.  In  some  South 
African  languages  there  is  no  special  term  for  the  father's  sister; 
thus  in  Xosa,  she  is  denoted  by  a  descriptive  term  udade  ho  hawo, 
literally  'father's  sister'.  In  Zulu  she  may  be  referred  to  by  a 
similar  descriptive  term  or  she  may  be  spoken  of  simply  as  ubaba, 
'father',  just  like  the  father's  brothers.  In  the  Friendly  Islands 
the  mother's  brother  may  be  denoted  by  a  special  term  tuasitia, 
or  he  may  be  called  fu'e  tangata,  literally  'male  mother'.  This 
similarity  between  South  Africa  and  Polynesia  cannot,  I  think, 
be  regarded  as  accidental;  yet  there  is  no  possible  connection 
between  the  Polynesian  languages  and  the  Bantu  languages,  and 
I  find  it  very  difficult  to  conceive  that  the  two  regions  have  adopted 
the  custom  of  calling  the  mother's  brother  by  a  term  meaning 
'male  mother'  either  from  one  another  or  from  one  common 
source. 

Now  let  us  see  if  we  can  deduce  what  ought  to  be  the  patterns 
of  behaviour  towards   the  mother's   brother   and   the   father's 


20  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

sister  in  a  patrilineal  society  on  the  basis  of  the  principle  or 
tendency  which  I  have  suggested  is  present.  I'o  do  this  we  must 
first  know  the  patterns  for  the  father  and  the  mother  respectively, 
and  I  think  that  it  will,  perhaps,  be  more  reassuring  if  I  go  for 
the  definition  of  these  to  Mr.  Junod's  work,  as  his  observations 
will  certainly  not  have  been  influenced  by  the  hypothesis  that  I 
am  trying  to  prove. 
\^  The  relationship  of  father,  he  says,  'implies  respect  and  even 
fear.  The  father,  though  he  does  not  take  much  trouble  with 
his  children,  is,  however,  their  instructor,  the  one  who  scolds 
and  punishes.  So  do  also  the  father's  brothers'  (op.  cit.,  p.  222). 
I  Of  a  man's  own  mother  he  says:  'She  is  his  true  mamana,  and  this 
/  relation  is  very  deep  and  tender,  combining  respect  with  love. 
Love,  however,  generally  exceeds  respect'  (op.  cit.,  p.  224). 
Of  the  mother's  relation  to  her  children  we  read  that  'She  is 
generally  weak  with  them  and  is  often  accused  by  the  father  of 
spoiling  them.' 

r  There  is  some  danger  in  condensed  formulae,  but  I  think 
we  shall  not  be  far  wrong  in  saying  that  in  a  strongly  patriarchal 
society,  such  as  we  find  in  South  Africa,  the  father  is  the  one  w^ho 
must  be  respected  and  obeyed,  and  the  mother  is  the  one  from 
whom  may  be  expected  tenderness  and  indulgence.  I  could  show 
you,  if  it  were  necessary,  that  the  same  thing  is  true  of  the  family 
life  of  the  Friendly  Islanders. 

If,  now,  we  apply  the  principle  that  I  have  suggested  is  at 
work  in  these  peoples  it  will  follov/  that  the  father's  sister  is 
one  who  must  be  obeyed  and  treated  with  respect,  while  from  the 
mother's  brother  indulgence  and  care  may  be  looked  for.  But  the 
matter  is  complicated  by  another  factor.  If  we  consider  the  relation 
of  a  nephew  to  his  uncle  and  aunt,  the  question  of  sex  comes  in. 
In  primitive  societies  there  is  a  marked  difference  in  the  behaviour 
of  a  man  towards  other  men  and  that  towards  women.  Risking 
once  more  a  formula,  we  may  say  that  any  considerable  degree 
of  familiarity  is  generally  only  permitted  in  such  a  society  as  the 
BaThonga  between  persaijs  of  the  same  sex.  A  man  must  treat 
his  female  relatives  with  greater  respect  than  his  male  relatives. 
Consequently  the  nephew  must  treat  his  father's  sister  with  even 
greater  respect  than  he  does  his  own  father.  (In  just  the  same  way, 
owing  to  the  principle  of  respect  for  age  or  seniority,  a  man  must 
treat  his  father's  elder  brother  with  more  respect  than  his  own 


THE    MOTHER  S    BROTHER    IN    SOUTH   AFRICA  21 

father.)  Inversely,  a  man  may  treat  his  mother's  brother,  who  is  of 
his  own  sex,  with  a  degree  of  famiHarity  that  would  not  be  possible 
with  any  w^oman,  even  his  own  mother.  The  influence  of  sex 
on  the  behaviour  of  kindred  is  best  seen  in  the  relations  of  brother 
and  sister.  In  the  Friendly  Islands  and  amongst  the  Nama  a  man 
must  pay  great  respect  to  his  sister,  particularly  his  eldest  sister, 
and  may  never  indulge  in  any  familiarities  with  her.  The  same 
thing  is  true,  I  believe,  of  the  South  African  Bantu.  In  many 
primitive  societies  the  father's  sister  and  the  elder  sisters  are  the 
objects  of  the  same  general  kind  of  behaviour,  and  in  some  of 
these  the  two  kinds  of  relatives  are  classified  together  and  denoted 
by  the  same  name. 

We  have  deduced  from  our  assumed  principle  a  certain  pattern  "^ 
of  behaviour  for  the  father's  sister  and  for  the  mother's  brother. 
Now  these  patterns  are  exactly  what  we  find  amongst  the 
BaThonga,  amongst  the  Hottentots,  and  in  the  Friendly  Islands. 
The  father's  sister  is  above  all  relatives  the  one  to  be  respected  and 
obeyed.  The  mother's  brother  is  the  one  relative  above  all  from 
whom  we  may  expect  indulgence,  with  whom  we  may  be  familiar 
and  take  liberties.  Here,  then,  is  an  alternative  'possible  ex- 
planation' of  the  customs  relating  to  the  mother's  brother,  and 
it  has  this  advantage  over  Mr.  Junod's  theory  that  it  also  explains 
the  correlated  customs  relating  to  the  father's  sister.  TKis  brings 
us,  however,  not  to  the  end  but  to  the  beginning  of  our  enquiry. 
It  is  easy  enough  to  invent  hypotheses.  The  important  and  difficult 
work  begins  when  we  set  out  to  verify  them.  It  will  be  impossible 
for  me,  in  the  short  time  available,  to  make  any  attempt  to  verify 
the  hypothesis  I  have  put  before  you.  All  I  can  do  is  to  point 
out  certain  lines  of  study  which  will,  I  believe,  provide  that 
verification. 

The  first  and  most  obvious  thing  to  do  is  to  study  in  detail 
the  behaviour  of  the  sister's  son  and  the  mother's  brother  to 
one  another  in  matriarchal  societies.  Unfortunately,  there  is 
practically  no  information  on  this  subject  relating  to  Africa,  and 
very  little  for  any  other  part  of  the  world.  Moreover,  there  are 
certain  false  ideas  connected  with  this  distinction  of  societies 
into  matriarchal  and  patriarchal  that  it  is  necessary  to  remove 
before  we  attempt  to  go  further. 

In  all  societies,  primitive  or  advanced,  kinship  is  necessarily 
bilateral.  The  individual  is  related  to  certain  persons  through  his 


22  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

father  and  to  others  through  his  mother,  and  the  kinship  system 
of  the  society  lays  down  what  shall  be  the  character  of  his  dealings 
with  his  paternal  relatives  and  his  maternal  relatives  respectively. 
But  society  tends  to  divide  into  segments  (local  groups,  lineages, 
clans,  etc.),  and  when  the  hereditary  principle  is  accepted,  as  it 
most  frequently  is,  as  the  means  of  determining  the  membership 
of  a  segment,  then  it  is  necessary  to  choose  between  maternal 
or  paternal  descent.  When  a  society  is  divided  into  groups  with  a 
rule  that  the  children  belong  to  the  group  of  the  father  we  have 
patrilineal  descent,  while  if  the  children  always  belong  to  the 
group  of  the  mother  the  descent  is  matrilineal. 

There  is,  unfortunately,  a  great  deal  of  looseness  in  the 
use  of  the  terms  matriarchal  and  patriarchal,  and  for  that  reason 
many  anthropologists  refuse  to  use  them.  If  we  are  to  use  them  at 
all,  we  must  first  give  exact  definitions.  A  society  may  be  called 
patriarchal  when  descent  is  patrilineal  (i.e.  the  children  belong 
to  the  group  of  the  father),  marriage  is  patrilocal  (i.e.  the  wife 
removes  to  the  local  group  of  the  husband),  inheritance  (of 
property)  and  succession  (to  rank)  are  in  the  male  line,  and  jhe 
family  is  patripotestal  (i.e.  the  authority  over  the  members  of  the 
family  is  in  the  hands  of  the  father  or  his  relatives).  On  the 
other  hand,  a  society  can  be  called  matriarchal  when  descent, 
inheritance  and  succession  are  in  the  female  line,  marriage  is 
matrilocal  (the  husband  removing  to  the  home  of  his  wife),  and 
when  the  authority  over  the  children  is  wielded  by  the  mother's 
relatives. 

If  this  definition  of  these  opposing  terms  is  accepted,  it 
is  at  once  obvious  that  a  great  number  of  primitive  societies  are 
neither  matriarchal  nor  patriarchal,  though  some  may  incline 
more  to  the  one  side,  and  others  more  to  the  other.  Thus,  if  we 
examine  the  tribes  of  Eastern  Australia,  which  are  sometimes 
spoken  of  as  matriarchal,  we  find  that  marriage  is  patrilocal,  so  that 
membership  of  the  local  group  is  inherited  in  the  male  line,  the 
authority  over  the  children  is  chiefly  in  the  hands  of  the  father  and 
his  brothers,  property  (what  there  is  of  it)  is  mostly  inherited 
in  the  male  line,  while,  as  rank  is  not  recognised,  there  is  no 
question  of  succession.  The  only  matrilineal  institution  is  the  . 
descent  of  the  totemic  group,  which  is  through  the  mother,  so 
that  these  tribes,  so  far  from  being  matriarchal,  incline  rather 
to    the  patriarchal   side.  Kinship  amongst  them  is  thoroughly 


THE   MOTHER  S  BROTHER  IN   SOUTH   AFRICA  23 

bilateral,  but  for  most  purposes  kinship  through  the  father  is  of 
more  importance  than  kinship  through  the  mother.  There  is  some 
evidence,  for  example,  that  the  obligation  to  avenge  a  death  falls 
upon  the  relatives  in  the  male  line  rather  than  upon  those  in  the 
female  line. 

We  find  an  interesting  instance  of  this  bilateralism,  if  it  may 
be  so  called,  in  South  Africa,  in  the  OvaHerero  tribe.  The  facts 
are  not  quite  certain,  but  it  would  seem  that  this  tribe  is  sub- 
divided into  two  sets  of  segments  crossing  one  another.  For  one 
set  (the  omaanda)  descent  is  matrilineal,  while  for  the  other  (otuzo) 
it  is  patrilineal.  A  child  belongs  to  the  eanda  of  its  mother  and 
inherits  cattle  from  its  mother's  brothers,  but  belongs  to  the  oruzo 
of  its  father  and  inherits  his  ancestral  spirits.  Authority  over  the 
children  would  seem  to  be  in  the  hands  of  the  father  and  his 
brothers  and  sisters. 

It  is  now  clear,  I  hope,  that  the  distinction  between  matriarchal 
and  patriarchal  societies  is  not  an  absolute  but  a  relative  one. 
Even  in  the  most  strongly  patriarchal  society  some  social  im- 
portance is  attached  to  kinship  through  the  mother;  and  similarly 
in  the  most  strongly  matriarchal  society  the  father  and  his  kindred 
are  always  of  some  importance  in  the  life  of  the  individual. 

In  Africa  we  have  in  the  south-east  a  group  of  tribes  that 
incline  strongly  to  patriarchy,  so  much  so,  in  fact,  that  we  may 
perhaps  justifiably  speak  of  them  as  patriarchal.  Descent  of 
the  social  group,  inheritance  of  property,  succession  to  chieftain- 
ship, are  all  in  the  male  line;  marriage  is  patrilocal,  and  authority 
in  the  family  is  strongly  patripotestal.  In  the  north  of  Africa,  in 
Kenya  and  the  surrounding  countries,  there  is  another  group  of 
strongly  patriarchal  peoples,  some  of  them  Bantu-speaking,  while 
others  are  Nilotic  or  Hamitic.  Between  these  two  patriarchal 
regions  there  is  a  band  of  peoples  stretching  apparently  right 
across  Africa  from  east  to  west,  on  the  level  of  Nyasaland  and 
Northern  Rhodesia,  in  which  the  tendency  is  towards  matriarchal 
institutions.  Descent  of  the  social  group,  inheritance  of  property, 
and  succession  to  the  kingship  or  chieftainship  are  in  the  female 
line.  In  some  of  the  tribes  marriage  seems  to  be  matrilocal,  at  any 
rate  temporarily  if  not  permanently,  i.e.  a  man  on  marriage  has  to 
go  and  live  with  his  wife's  people. 

It  is  about  these  people  and  their  customs  that  we  urgently 
need  information  if  we  are  to  understand  such  matters  as  the 


24  S'iRUCTURE   AND    lUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVE    SOCIETY 

subject  of  this  paper.  Of  one  tribe  of  this  region  we  have  a  fairly 
full  description  in  the  vi^ork  of  Smith  and  Dale  {The  Ila-speaking 
People  of  Northern  Rhodesia,  1920).  Unfortunately,  on  the  very 
points  with  which  I  am  now  dealing  the  information  is  scanty  and 
certainly  very  incomplete.  There  are,  however,  two  points  I  wish 
to  bring  out.  The  first  concerns  the  behaviour  of  the  mother's 
brother  to  his  sister's  son.  We  are  told  that  'the  mother's  brother 
is  a  personage  of  vast  importance;  having  the  power  even  of  life 
and  death  over  his  nephews  and  nieces,  which  no  other  relations, 
not  even  the  parents,  have;  he  is  to  be  held  in  honour  even  above 
the  father.  This  is  avunculi  potestas,  which  among  the  Balla  is 
greater  than  patria  potestas.  In  speaking  of  the  mother's  brother, 
it  is  customary  to  use  an  honorific  title  given  to  people  who  are  re- 
spected very  highly'  (op.  cit..  Vol.  I,  p.  230).  This  kind  of  relation 
between  the  mother's  brother  and  the  sister's  son  is  obviously 
what  we  might  expect  in  a  strongly  matriarchal  society.  But  how 
then,  on  Mr.  Junod's  theory,  can  we  explain  the  change  which 
must  have  taken  place  from  this  sort  of  relation  to  that  which  now 
exists  among  the  BaThonga? 

This  brings  me  to  another  point  which  it  will  not  be  possible 
to  discuss  in  detail  but  which  has  an  important  bearing  on  the 
argument.  We  have  been  considering  the  relation  of  the  sister's 
son  to  his  mother's  brother;  but  if  we  are  to  reach  a  really  final 
explanation,  we  must  study  also  the  behaviour  of  a  man  to  his 
other  relatives  on  the  mother's  side,  and  to  his  mother's  group 
as  a  whole.  Now  in  the  Friendly  Islands  the  peculiar  relation 
between  a  sister's  son  and  a  mother's  brother  exists  also  between 
a  daughter's  son  and  his  mother's  father.  The  daughter's  son 
must  be  honoured  by  his  grandfather.  He  is  'a  chief  to  him. 
He  may  take  his  grandfather's  property,  and  he  may  take  away 
the  ofi'ering  that  his  grandfather  makes  to  the  gods  at  a  kava 
ceremony.  The  mother's  father  and  the  mother's  brother  are  the 
objects  of  very  similar  behaviour  patterns,  of  which  the  out- 
standing feature  is  the  indulgence  on  the  one  side  and  the  liberty 
permitted  on  the  other.  Now  there  is  evidence  of  the  same  thing 
amongst  the  BaThonga,  but  again  we  lack  the  full  information 
that  we  need.  Mr.  Junod  WTites  that  a  grandfather  'is  more  lenient 
to  his  grandson  by  his  daughter  than  his  grandson  by  his  son' 
(op  cit.  p.  227).  In  this  connection  the  custom  of  calling  the 
mother's  brother  kokwana  (grandfather)  is  significant. 


THE   mother's  brother   IN   SOUTH   AFRICA  2$ 

Now  here  is  something  that  it  seems  impossible  to  explain 
on  Mr.  Ju nod's  theory.  In  a  strongly  matriarchal  society  the 
mother's  father  does  not  belong  to  the  same  group  as  his  grand- 
child and  is  not  a  person  from  whom  property  can  be  inherited 
or  who  can  exercise  authority.  Any  explanation  of  the  liberties 
permitted  towards  the  mother's  brother  cannot  be  satisfactory 
unless  it  also  explains  the  similar  liberties  towards  the  mother's 
father  which  are  found  in  Polynesia,  and  apparently  to  some  extent 
in  South  Africa.  This  Mr,  Junod's  theoii^  clearly  does  not  do, 
and  cannot  do. 

But  on  the  hypothesis  that  I  have  put  forw^ard  the  matter! 
is  fairly  simple.  In  primitive  society  there  is  a  strongly  marked 
tendency  to  merge  the  individual  in  the  group  to  which  he  or  shei 
belongs.  The  result  of  this  in  relation  to  kinship  is  a  tendency 
to  extend  to  all  the  members  of  a  group  a  certain  type  of  behaviour' 
which  has  its  origin  in  a  relationship  to  one  particular  member 
of  the  group.  Thus  the  tendency  in  the  BaThonga  tribe  would 
seem  to  be  to  extend  to  all  the  members  of  the  mother's  group 
(family  or  lineage)  a  certain  pattern  of  behaviour  which  is  derived 
from  the  special  pattern  that  appears  in  the  behaviour  of  a  son  i., 
towards  his  mother.  Since  it  is  from  his  mother  that  he  expects     I 
care  and  indulgence  he  looks  for  the  same  sort  of  treatment  from    1 
the  people  of  his  mother's  group,  i.e.  from  all  his  maternal  kin.  y^ 
On  the  other  hand  it  is  to  his  paternal  kin  that  he  owes  obedience 
and  respect.  The  patterns  that  thus  arise  in  relation  to  the.father_ 
and  the  mother  are_generalised  and  extended  to  the  kindred 
on  the  one  side  and  on  the  other.  If  I  had  time  I  think  I  could 
show  you  quite  conclusively  that  this  is  really  the  principle  that 
governs  the  relations  between  an  individual  and  his  mother's 
kindred  in  the  patriarchal  tribes  of  South  Africa.  I  must  leave  the 
demonstration,  however,  to  another  occasion.  I  can  do  no  more 
now  than  illustrate  my  statement. 

The  custom,  often  miscalled  bride-purchase  and  generally 
known  in  South  Africa  asjo^o/^jis,  as  Mr.  Junod  has  well  shown,  a 
payment  made  in  compensation  to  a  girl's  family  for  her  loss  when 
she  is  taken  away  in  marriage.  Now,  since  in  the  patriarchal  tribes- — 
of  South  Africa  a  woman  belongs  to  her  father's  people,  the  com- 
pensation has  to  be  paid  to  them.  But  you  will  find  that  in  many 
j)i  the  tribes  a  certain  portion  of  the  'marriage  payment'  is  handed 
over  to  the  mother's  brother  of  the  girl  for  whom  it  is  paid.  Thus, 


II 


26  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

amongst  the  BaPedi,  out  of  the  lenyalo  cattle  one  head  (called 
hloho)  is  handed  to  the  mother's  brother  of  the  girl.  Amongst  the 
BaSotho  a  portion  of  the  cattle  received  for  a  girl  on  her  marriage 
may  sometimes  be  taken  by  her  mother's  brother,  this  being 
known  as  ditsoa.  Now  the  natives  state  that  the  ditsoa  cattle 
received  by  the  mother's  brother  are  really  held  by  him  on  behalf 
of  his  sister's  children.  If  one  of  his  sister's  sons  or  daughters  is  ill 
he  may  be  required  to  offer  a  sacrifice  to  his  ancestral  spirits,  and 
he  then  takes  a  beast  from  the  ditsoa  herd.  Also,  when  the  sister's 
son  wishes  to  obtain  a  wife,  he  may  go  to  his  mother's  brother  to 
help  him  to  find  the  necessary  cattle  and  his  uncle  may  give  him 
some  of  the  ditsoa  cattle  received  at  the  marriage  of  his  sister,  or 
may  even  give  him  cattle  from  his  own  herd,  trusting  to  being  re- 
paid from  the  ditsoa  cattle  to  be  received  in  the  future  from  the 
marriage  of  a  niece.  I  believe  that  the  Native  Appeal  Court  has 
decided  that  the  payment  of  ditsoa  to  the  mother's  brother  is  a 
voluntary  matter  and  cannot  be  regarded  as  a  legal  obligation,  and 
with  that  judgment  I  am  in  agreement.  I  quote  this  custom 
because  it  illustrates  the  sort  of  interest  that  the  mother's  brother 
is  expected  to  take  in  his  sister's  son,  in  helping  him  and  looking 
after  his  welfare.  It  brings  us  back  to  the  question  as  to  why  the 
mother's  brother  may  be  asked  to  offer  sacrifices  when  his  nephew 
is  sick. 

In  south-east  Africa  ancestor  worship  is  patrilineal,  i.e.  a 
man  worships  and  takes  part  in  sacrifices  to  the  spirits  of  his 
deceased  relatives  in  the  male  line.  Mr.  Junod's  statements  about 
the  BaThonga  are  not  entirely  clear.  In  one  place  he  says  that 
each  family  has  two  sets  of  gods,  those  on  the  father's  side  and 
those  on  the  mother's;  they  are  equal  in  dignity  and  both  can  be 
invoked  (op.  cit.,  II,  p.  349,  and  I,  p.  256,  note).  But  in  another 
place  it  is  stated  that  if  an  offering  has  to  be  made  to  the  gods  of 
the  mother's  family  this  must  be  through  the  maternal  relatives, 
the  malume  (op.  cit.,  II,  p.  367).  Other  passages  confirm  this  and 
show  us  that  ancestral  spirits  can  only  be  directly  approached  in 
any  ritual  by  their  descendants  in  the  male  line. 

The  natives  of  the  Transkei  are  very  definite  in  their  state- 
ments to  me  that  a  person's  maternal  gods,  the  patrilineal  ancestors 
of  his  mother,  will  never  inflict  supernatural  punishment  upon 
him  by  making  him  sick.  (I  am  not  quite  so  sure  about  the  Sotho 
tribes,  but  I  think  that  they  probably  have  similar  views.)  On 


THE   MOTHER  S  BROTHER   IN   SOUTH  AFRICA  27 

the  Other  hand  a  married  woman  can  receive  protection  from  the 
ancestral  spirits  of  her  patrihneal  Hneage,  and  so  can  her  young 
children  as  long  as  they  are  attached  to  her.  For  children  are 
only  fully  incorporated  in  their  father's  lineage  when  they  reach 
adolescence.  So  in  the  Transkei  a  woman,  when  she  marries, 
should  be  given  a  cow,  the  uhidiinga  cow,  by  her  father,  from  the 
herd  of  her  lineage,  which  she  can  take  to  her  new  home.  Since 
she  may  not  drink  the  milk  from  her  husband's  herd  during 
the  early  period  of  her  married  life  she  can  be  provided  with 
milk  from  this  beast  that  comes  from  her  lineage.  This  cow 
constitutes  a  link  between  herself  and  her  lineage,  its  cattle,  and 
its  gods,  for  cattle  are  the  material  link  between  the  living  members 
of  the  lineage  and  the  ancestral  spirits.  So  if  she  is  sick  she  can 
make  for  herself  a  necklace  of  hairs  from  the  tail  of  this  cow  and 
so  put  herself  under  the  protection  of  her  lineage  gods.  Moreover, 
if  one  of  her  infant  children  is  sick,  she  can  make  a  similar 
necklace  which  is  thought  to  give  protection  to  the  child.  When 
her  son  is  grown  up  he  should  receive  an  uhulunga  bull  from  his 
father's  herd,  and  thereafter  it  is  from  the  tail  of  this  beast  that 
he  will  make  a  protective  amulet;  similarly  the  daughter,  when 
she  marries,  is  detached  from  her  mother,  and  may  receive  an 
iibulunga  cow  from  her  father. 

But  though,  according  to  the  statements  made  to  me,  the 
maternal  ancestors  vrill  not  punish  their  descendant  with  sickness, 
they  can  be  appealed  to  for  help.  When,  therefore,  a  child  is  sick 
the  parents  may  go  to  the  mother's  brother  of  the  child,  or  to  the 
mother's  father  if  he  is  still  living,  and  ask  that  a  sacrifice  shall 
be  offered,  and  an  appeal  for  help  made  to  the  child's  maternal 
ancestors.  This,  at  any  rate,  is  stated  as  a  practice  in  the  Sotho' 
tribes,  and  one  of  the  purposes  of  the  ditsoa  cattle  that  go  from  the 
marriage  payment  to  the  mother's  brother  of  the  bride  is  said  to 
be  to  make  provision  for  such  sacrifices  if  they  should  be  needed. 

This  brings  us  to  the  final  extension  of  the  principle  that' 
I  have  suggested  as  the  basis  of  the  customs  relating  to  the  mother's 
brother.  The  pattern  of  behaviour  towards  the  mother,  which  is 
developed  in  the  family  by  reason  of  the  nature  of  the  family 
group  and  its  social  life,  is  extended  with  suitable  modifications  to 
the  mother's  sister  and  to  the  mother's  brother,  then  to  the  group 
of  maternal  kindred  as  a  whole,  and  finally  to  the  maternal  gods, 
the  ancestors  of  the  mother's  group.  In  the  same  way  the  pattern 


28  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

of  behaviour  towards  the  father  is  extended  to  the  father's  brothers 
and  sisters,  and  to  the  whole  of  the  father's  group  (or  rather  to  all 
the  older  members  of  it,  the  principle  of  age  making  important 
modifications  necessary),  and  finally  to  the  paternal  gods. 

The  father  and  his  relatives  must  be  obeyed  and  respected 
(even  worshipped,  in  the  original  sense  of  the  word),  and  so 
therefore  also  must  be  the  paternal  ancestors.  The  father  punishes 
his  children,  and  so  may  the  ancestors  on  the  father's  side.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  mother  is  tender  and  indulgent  to  her  child, 
and  her  relatives  are  expected  to  be  the  same,  and  so  also  the 

t.ernal  spirits. 
A  very  important  principle,  which  I  have  tried  to  demonstrate 
elsewhere  {The  Andaman  Islanders,  Chapter  V),  is  that  the  social 
values  current  in  a  primitive  society  are  maintained  by  being 
expressed  in  ceremonial  or  ritual  customs.  The  set  of  values 
that  we  here  meet  with  in  the  relations  of  an  individual  to  his 
kindred  on  the  two  sides  must,  therefore,  also  have  their  proper 
ritual  expression.  The  subject  is  too  vast  to  deal  with  at  all 
adequately  here,  but  I  wish  to  discuss  one  point.  Amongst  the 
BaThonga,  and  also  in  Western  Polynesia  (Fiji  and  Tonga),  the 
sister's  son  (or  in  Tonga  also  the  daughter's  son)  intervenes  in  the 
sacrificial  ritual.  Mr.  Junod  describes  a  ceremony  of  crushing 
down  the  hut  of  a  dead  man  in  which  the  batukulu  (sister's  chil- 
dren) play  an  important  part.  They  kill  and  distribute  the  sacrificial 
victims  and  when  the  officiating  priest  makes  his  prayer  to  the 
spirit  of  the  dead  man  it  is  the  sister's  sons  who,  after  a  time, 
interrupt  oi*  *cut'  the  prayer  and  bring  it  to  an  end.  They  then, 
among  the  BaThonga  clans,  seize  the  portions  of  the  sacrifice 
that  have  been  dedicated  to  the  spirit  of  the  dead  man  and  run 
away  with  them,  'stealing'  them  (op.  cit.,  I,  p.  162).^^ 

I  would  suggest  that  the  meaning  of  this  iS'THat  it  gives  a 
ritual  expression  to  the  special  relation  that  exists  between  the 
sister's  son  and  the  mother's  brother.  When  the  uncle  is  alive 
the  nephews  have  the  right  to  go  to  his  village  and  take  his  food. 
Now  that  he  is  dead  they  come  and  do  this  again,  as  part  of  the 
funeral  ritual,  and  as  it  were  for  the  last  time,  i.e.  they  come  and 
steal  portions  of  meat  and  beer  that  are  put  aside  as  the  portion  of 
the  deceased  man. 

The  same  sort  of  explanation  will  be  found  to  hold,  I  think, 
of  the  part  played  in  sacrificial  and  other  ritual  by  the  sister's 


THE   MOTHER  S   BROTHER    IN   SOUTH    AFRICA  29 

son  both  amongst  the  Bantu  of  South  Africa  and  also  in  Tonga 
and  Fiji.  As  a  man  fears  his  father,  so  he  fears  and  reverences  his 
paternal  ancestors,  but  he  has  no  fear  of  his  mother's  brother, 
and  so  may  act  irreverently  to  his  maternal  ancestors;  he  is, 
indeed,  required  by  custom  so  to  act  on  certain  occasions,  thus 
giving  ritual  expression  to  the  special  social  relations  between  a 
man  and  his  maternal  relatives  in  accordance  with  the  general 
function  of  ritual,  as  I  understand  it. 

It  will,  perhaps,  be  of  help  if  I  give  you  a  final  brief  statement 
of  the  hypothesis  I  am  advancing,  with  the  assumptions  involved 
in  it  and  some  of  its  important  implications. 

1.  The  characteristic  of  most  of  these  societies  that  we 
call  primitive  is  that  the  conduct  of  individuals  to  one 
another  is  very  largely  regulated  on  the  basis  of  kinship, 
this  being  brought  about  by  the  formation  of  fixed  patterns 
of  behaviour  for  each  recognised  kind  of  kinship  relation. 

2.  This  is  sometimes  associated  with  a  segmentary  organisation 
of  society,  i.e.  a  condition  in  which  the  whole  society  is 
divided  into  a  number  of  segments  (lineages,  clans). 

3.  While  kinship  is  ahvays  and  necessarily  bilateral,  or 
cognatic,  the  segmentary  organisation  requires  the  adoption 
of  the  uniHneal  principle,  and  a  choice  has  to  be  made 
between  patrilineal  and  matrilineal  institutions. 

4.  In  patrihneal  societies  of  a  certain  type,  the  special  pattern 
of  behaviour  between  a  sister's  son  and  the  mother's 
brother  is  derived  from  the  pattern  of  behaviour  between 
the  child  and  the  mother,  which  is  itself  the  product  of  the 
social  life  within  the  family  in  the  narrow  sense. 

5.  This  same  kind  of  behaviour  tends  to  be  extended  to  all 
the  maternal  relatives,  i.e.  to  the  whole  family  or  group  to 
which  the  mother's  brother  belongs.^ 

^  This  extension  from  the  mother's  brother  to  the  other  maternal  relatives 
is  shown  in  the  BaThonga  tribe  in  the  kinship  terminology.  The  term  malunie, 
primarily  applied  to  the  mother's  brother,  is  extended  to  the  sons  of  those  men, 
who  are  also  malume.  If  my  mother's  brothers  are  dead  it  is  their  sons  who  will 
have  to  sacrifice  on  my  behalf  to  my  inaternal  ancestors.  In  the  northern  part 
of  the  tribe  the  term  malume  has  gone  out  of  use,  and  the  mother's  father, 
the  mother's  brother,  and  the  sons  of  the  mother's  brother  are  all  called 
kokzvana  (grandfather).  However  absurd  it  may  seem  to  us  to  call  a  mother's 
brother's  son,  who  may  be  actually  younger  than  the  speaker,  by  a  word 
meaning  'grandfather',  the  argument  of  this  paper  will  enable  us  to  see  some 
meaning  in  it.  The  person  who  must  sacrifice  on  my  behalf  to  my  maternal 


30  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

6.  In  societies  with  patrilineal  ancestor  worship  (such  as 
the  BaThonga  and  the  Friendly  Islanders)  the  same  type  of 
behaviour  may  also  be  extended  to  the  gods  of  the  mother's 
family. 

7,  The  special  kind  of  behaviour  to  the  maternal  relatives 
(living  and  dead)  or  to  the  maternal  group  and  its  gods  and 
sacra,  is  expressed  in  definite  ritual  customs,  the  function 
of  ritual  here,  as  elsewhere,  being  to  fix  and  make  permanent 
certain  types  of  behaviour,  with  the  obligations  and  senti- 
ments involved  therein. 

In  conclusion,  may  I  point  out  that  I  have  selected  the  subject 
of  my  contribution  to  this  meeting  because  it  is  one  not  only  of 
theoretical  but  also  of  practical  interest.  For  instance,  there  is  the 
question  as  to  whether  the  Native  Appeal  Court  was  really  right 
in  its  judgment  that  the  payment  of  the  ditsoa  cattle  to  the  mother's 
brother  of  a  bride  is  not  a  legal  but  only  a  moral  obligation.  So 
far  as  I  have  been  able  to  form  an  opinion,  I  should  say  that 
the  judgment  was  right. 

■  The  whole  subject  of  the  payments  at  marriage  [lohola)  is 
/one  of  considerable  practical  importance  at  the  present  time  to 
missionaries  and  magistrates,  and  to  the  natives  themselves.  Now 
the  study  of  the  exact  position  in  which  a  person  stands  to  his 
maternal  relatives  is  one  without  which  it  is  impossible  to  arrive 
at  a  completely  accurate  understanding  of  the  customs  of  lobola. 
One  of  the  chief  functions  of  lohola  is  to  fix  the  social  position  of 
the  children  of  a  marriage.  If  the  proper  payment  is  made  by  a 
family,  then  the  children  of  the  woman  w^ho  comes  to  them  in 
exchange  for  the  cattle  belong  to  that  family,  and  its  gods  are  their 
gods.  The  natives  consider  that  the  strongest  of  all  social  bonds  is 
that  between  a  child  and  its  mother,  and  therefore  by  the  ex- 
tension that  inevitably  takes  place  there  is  a  very  strong  bond 
between  the  child  and  its  mother's  family.  The  function  of  the 
lohola  payment  is  not  to  destroy  but  to  modify  this  bond,  and  to 
place  the  children  definitely  in  the  father's  family  and  group  for 
all  matters  concerning  not  only  the  social  but  also  the  religious 

ancestors  is  first  my  mother's  father,  then,  if  he  is  dead,  my  mother's  brother, 
and  after  the  decease  of  the  latter,  his  son,  who  may  be  younger  than  I  am. 
There  is  a  similarity  of  function  for  these  three  relationships,  a  single  general 
pattern  of  behaviour  for  me  towards  them  all  and  this  is  again  similar  in  general 
to  that  for  grandfathers.     The  nomenclature  is,  therefore,  appropriate. 


THE  MOTHERS   BROTHER   IN   SOUTH   AFRICA  3 1 

life  of  the  tribe.  If  no  lobola  is  paid  the  child  inevitably  belongs 
to  the  mother's  family,  though  its  position  is  then  irregular. 
But  the  \A  Oman  for  whom  the  lobola  is  paid  does  not  become  a 
member  of  the  husband's  family;  their  gods  are  not  her  gods; 
and  that  is  the  final  test.  I  have  said  enough,  I  hope,  to  show  that 
the  proper  understanding  of  customs  relating  to  the  mother's- 
brother  is  a  necessary  preliminary  to  any  final  theory  of  lobola. 


CHAPTER     II 

PATRILINEAL  AND  MATRILINEAL  SUCCESSION  i 

IF  we  are  to  understand  aright  the  laws  and  customs  of  non- 
European  peoples  we  must  be  careful  not  to  interpret  them  in 
terms  of  our  own  legal  conceptions,  which,  simple  and  obvious 
as  some  of  them  may  seem  to  us,  are  the  product  of  a  long  and 
complex  historical  development  and  are  special  to  our  own  culture. 
If,  for  instance,  we  attempt  to  apply  to  the  customs  of  the  simpler 
peoples  our  own  precise  distinctions  between  the  law  relating  to 
persons  and  the  law  relating  to  things  we  shall  produce  nothing 
but  confusion  in  the  result. 

With  us  one  of  the  most  important  aspects  of  succession  is 
the  transmission  of  property  by  inheritance.  Yet  in  some  of  the 
simplest  societies  this  is  a  matter  of  almost  no  significance  at  all. 
In  an  Australian  tribe,  for  example,  a  man  possesses  a  few  weapons, 
tools,  utensils  and  personal  ornaments,  things  of  little  value  or 
permanence.  On  his  death  some  of  them  may  be  destroyed,  others 
may  be  distributed  among  his  relatives  and  friends.  But  their 
disposal  is  of  so  little  importance,  unless  in  relation  to  ritual, 
that  it  is  often  difficult  to  find  any  rules  of  customary  procedure. 
But  even  in  such  simple  societies,  where  inheritance  of  private 
property  may  be  said  not  to  exist  or  to  be  of  minimal  importance, 
there  are  problems  of  succession  in  the  widest  sense  of  the  term. 
The  term  'succession'  will  here  be  taken  as  referring  to  the 
transmission  of  rights  in  general.  A  right  exists  in,  and  is  de- 
finable in  terms  of,  recognised  social  usage.  A  right  may  be 
that  of  an  individual  or  a  collection  of  individuals.  It  may  be 
defined  as  a  measure  of  control  that  a  person,  or  a  collection  of 
persons,  has  over  the  acts  of  some  person  or  persons,  said  to  be 
thereby  made  liable  to  the  performance  of  a  duty.  Rights  may  be 
classified  as  of  three  main  kinds: 

(a)  Rights  over  a  person  imposing  some  duty  or  duties  upon 

that  person.  This  is  the  jus  in  personam  of  Roman  law. 

A  father  may  exercise  such  rights  over  his  son,  or  a  nation 

over  its  citizens. 

'  Reprinted  from  The  lozva  Lazv  Reviezv,  \'ol.  XX,  No.  2,  January  1935. 

32 


PATRILINEAL   AND   MATRILINEAL  SUCCESSION  33 

(b)  Rights  over  a  person  'as  against  the  world',  i.e.  imposing 
duties  on  all  other  persons  in  respect  of  that  particular 
person.  This  is  the  jus  in  rem  of  Roman  law  in  relation  to 
persons. 

{c)  Rights  over  a  thing,  i.e.  some  object  other  than  a  person, 
as  against  the  world,  imposing  duties  on  other  persons  in 
relation  to  that  thing. 

The  rights  classified  under  {b)  and  (c)  are  fundamentally  of 
the  same  kind,  distinguished  only  as  they  relate  to  persons  or  to 
things,  and  are  of  a  different  kind  from  those  classified  under  {a). 

We  may  consider  a  few  examples  from  such  a  simple  society 
as  an  Australian  tribe.  A  man  has  certain  rights  over  his  wife. 
Some  of  them  are  rights  in  personam  whereby  he  may  require  from 
her  the  performance  of  certain  duties.  Others  are  rights  in  rem. 
If  anyone  should  kill  the  wife  he  commits  an  injury  against  the 
husband.  If  anyone  should  have  sexual  intercourse  with  the  wife 
without  the  consent  of  the  husband  he  commits  an  injury  against 
the  latter.  In  some  tribes  a  man  may  lend  his  wife  to  another;  this 
is  an  exercise  by  the  husband  both  of  his  rights  in  personam  and  of 
his  rights  in  rem. 

In  a  great  number  of  Australian  tribes  the  custom  of  the 
levirate  holds  sway.  By  this,  when  a  man  dies  all  his  rights  over 
his  wife  (and  over  his  immature  children)  are  transferred  to  his 
younger  brother,  or  failing  such,  to  an  agnatic  cousin.  This  is 
a  simple  instance  of  fraternal  succession.  What  is  transferred  is 
certain  rights  in  perso?iam  and  in  rem  over  certain  persons  (the  wife 
and  children)  and  with  these  rights  there  go,  of  course,  certain 
obligations  or  duties. 

Let  us  next  consider,  in  such  a  tribe  as  the  Kariera  of  Western 
Australia,  the  nature  of  the  group  that  I  shall  call  a  'horde'. 
iTfiis  is  a  body  of  persons  who  jointly  possess,  occupy  and'^p^loiTa-^ 
certain  defined  area  of  cotrrltryl  The  rights  of  the  horde  over  its 
territory  can  be  briefly  indicStM  by  saying  that  no  person  who  is 
not  a  member  of  the  horde  has  the  right  to  any  animal,  vegetable 
or  mineral  product  from  the  territory  except  by  invitation  or 
consent  of  members  of  the  horde.  Acts  of  trespass  against  this 
exclusive  right  of  a  horde  to  its  territory  seem  to  have  been  very 
rare  in  the  social  life  of  the  aborigines  but  it  appears  to  have  been 
generally  held  that  anyone  conmiitting  such  a  trespass  could 

2 


34  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

justifiably  be  killed.^  This  exclusive  use  of  its  territory  by  a  horde 
is  modified  by  obligations  of  hospitality  whereby,  when  there  is  an 
abundance  of  some  kind  of  food  at  a  certain  time,  members  of 
friendly  neighbouring  hordes  are  invited  to  come  in  and  share  it. 
The  son  of  any  woman  born  in  the  horde  and  married  elsewhere 
is  always^-entitled  to  visit  his  mother's  horde  and  hunt  in  its 
territory.  / 

It  is^convenient  to  speak  of  such  a  group  as  the  Kariera  horde 
as  a  'corporation'  having  an  'estate'.  This  is  an  extension  of  the 
terms  'corporation'  and  'estate'  as  they  are  commonly  used  in  law, 
but  I  think  this  extension  is  justifiable,  and  hope  that  at  any  rate 
it  will  be  admitted  for  the  purposes  of  the  present  exposition.  By 
an  estate  is  here  meant  a  collection  of  rights  (whether  over  persons 
or  things)  with  the  implied  duties,  the  unity  of  which  is  constituted 
either  by  the  fact  that  they  are  the  rights  of  a  single  person  and 
can  be  transmitted,  as  a  whole,  or  in  division,  to  some  other 
person  or  persons,  or  that  they  are  the  rights  of  a  defined  group 
(the  corporation)  which  maintains  a  continuity  of  possession.  A 
personal  estate  thus  corresponds  to  that  universitas  juris  which  is 
what,  in  Roman  law,  was  transmitted  by  inheritance.  ^  .  .  . 

The  corporate  estate  of  a  Kariera  horde  includes  in  the  first 
place  its  rights  over  its  territory.  The  continuity  of  the  horde 
is  maintained  by  the  continuity  of  possession  of  the  territory, 
which  remains  constant,  not  subject  to  division  or  increase,  for 
the  Australian  aborigines  have  no  conception  of  the  possibility 
of  territorial  conquest  by  armed  force.  The  relation  of  a  horde 
to  its  territory  does  not  correspond  exactly  to  what  we  regard  as 
'ownership'  in  modern  law.  It  has  some  of  the  qualities  of  corpor- 
ate ownership,  but  also  partakes  of  the  nature  of  the  relation  of 
a  modern  state  to  its  territory,  which  we  may  speak  of  as  the 
exercise  of  'dominion'.  Rights  of  ownership  over  land  and  rights 
of  dominion  have  seemingly  both  had  their  origin  by  development 
and  differentiation  from  such  a  simple  relation  as  that  exemplified 
in  the  Australian  horde. 

^  We  have  records  from  a  part  of  South  Australia  of  occasional  deliberate 
acts  of  trespass  with  armed  force,  a  body  of  men  invading  a  territory  in  which 
red  ochre  was  found  for  the  purpose  of  obtaining  a  supply.  This  was  actually 
an  act  of  war  and  as  the  invaders  took  care  to  come  in  force  the  horde  whose 
rights  were  thus  invaded  had  no  effective  remedy. 

^  Hereditas  est  successio  in  universum  jus  quod  defunctus  habuit:  an  inheritance 
is  a  succession  to  the  entire  legal  position  of  a  deceased  man. 


PATRILINEAL  AND  MATRILINEAL  SUCCESSION  35 

The  estate  of  a  horde  includes  not  only  its  rights  over  a 
territory,  but  also  its  rights,  in  personam  and  in  rem,  over  its 
members.  The  adult  male  members  of  the  horde  owe  certain 
duties  to  it  so  that  it  has  rights  in  personam  over  them.  It  also  has 
rights  in  rem,  for  if  one  of  them  is  killed,  by  violence  or  by  sorcery, 
the  horde  as  a  whole  conceives  itself  to  have  been  injured  and 
takes  steps  to  obtain  satisfaction.  Women  and  children  are  not 
members  of  the  horde  in  the  same  sense  as  adult  males.  If  a 
man's  wife  is  'stolen'  it  is  he  as  an  individual  who  seeks  satisfaction 
though  he  will  have  the  backing  of  the  other  members  of  the  horde. 
But  indirectly  she  also  belongs  to  the  horde  so  that  when  her 
husband  dies  she  should  by  custom  pass  into  the  possession  of  some 
other  member  of  the  horde  and  not  to  some  person  outside. 

Since  the  Kariera  horde  is  exogamous  every  female  child 
passes  by  marriage  out  of  the  possession  of  her  parents  and  out  of 
the  possession  of  the  horde  into  the  possession  of  her  husband  in 
another  horde.  By  Australian  custom  this  transfer  of  possession, 
i.e.  of  rights,  in  personam  and  in  rem,  over  a  person,  should 
normally  involve  compensation  or  indemnification,  which,  in  many 
tribes,  is  provided  by  the  man  who  receives  a  wife  giving  his 
sister  in  exchange  to  be  the  wife  of  his  brother-in-law.  Male 
children  may  be  said  to  pass  out  of  the  possession  of  the  parents 
and  into  direct  possession  of  the  horde  at  initiation.  This  is, 
in  some  tribes,  symbolically  expressed  in  the  initiation  ritual. 

The  Kariera  horde  affords  an  example  of  perpetual  corporate 
succession.  It  will  be  obvious,  I  think,  that  it  contains  the  germs 
of  the  state  and  of  sovereignty  as  we  know  them  in  more  complex 
developments.  Thus,  as  the  terms  have  been  used  above,  the 
United  States  of  America  is  a  'corporation'  having  as  its  con- 
stituent 'estate'  possession  of,  or  dominion  over,  a  certain  territory 
(subject,  unlike  that  of  an  Australian  horde,  to  increase  by  con- 
quest or  purchase)  and  certain  specific  rights,  in  personam  and 
in  rem,  over  the  persons  of  its  citizens. 

The  continuity  of  a  corporation  such  as  the  Australian  horde 
is  dependent  on  the  continuity  of  its  estate.  In  the  first  place 
there  is  continuity  of  possession  of  the  territory.  Secondly,  there 
is  a  continuity  which  transcends  the  space  of  a  human  life  by  the 
fact  that  as  the  group  loses  some  members  by  death  it  acquires 
new  members  by  the  birth  of  children  and  the  initiation  of  boys 
into  the  status  of  men. 


36  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVIi   SOCIETY 

If  now  we  turn  from  considering  the  horde  as  a  whole  to 
consider  the  individual  male  members  we  find  here  also  a  process 
of  customary  transmission  of  rights.  Children  'belong',  we  may 
say,  primarily  to  the  father,  i.e.  it  is  he  who  exercises  over  them 
rights  in  personam  and  in  rem.  As  the  father  in  turn  belongs  to 
the  horde  this  horde  has  some  rights  over  his  children.  When  a 
girl  reaches  puberty  the  rights  over  her  are  transferred  (perhaps 
not  in  entirety  but  in  great  part)  from  her  father  and  his  horde  to 
her  husband.  When  the  boy  reaches  puberty  he  is  transferred  from 
his  position  of  dependence  on  his  father  to  that  of  an  adult  member 
of  the  horde.  Now  a  member  of  the  horde  has  certain  rights  over 
other  members  and  over  the  territory  of  the  horde.  These  rights  are 
part  of  his  personal  estate  or  status.  Thus  there  is  a  process  of 
'patrilineal  succession'  whereby  the  sons  of  male  members  of  the 
horde  become  in  their  turn  members,  thus  acquiring  rights  and 
having  a  share  in  the  estate. 

We  are  thus  brought,  after  necessary  and  it  is  hoped  not  too 
tedious  preliminary  considerations,  to  the  problem  with  which  this 
paper  is  to  deal,  that  of  the  nature  and  function  of  the  unilineal 
transmission  of  rights.  In  the  patrilineal  succession  of  the 
Australian  horde  the  most  considerable  part  of  the  body  of  rights 
of  a  male  person,  his  status,  his  personal  estate  as  a  sharer  or 
co-parcener  in  the  estate  of  a  horde,  are  derived  by  liim  through 
his  father  to  the  exclusion  of  his  mother  and  are  transmitted  in 
turn  to  his  sons  to  the  exclusion  of  his  daughters.  It  is  important, 
however,  to  recognise  that  in  this  instance,  and,  so  far  as  we  know, 
in  all  instances  of  patrilineal  succession,  some  rights  are  also 
transmitted  through  the  mother.  Thus  in  the  Kariera  tribe  a  man 
has  certain  quite  important  rights  over  his  mother's  horde,  over 
its  individual  members,  and  over  its  territory. 

In  matrilineal  succession  the  greater  part  of  the  body  of 
rights  of  an  individual,  over  things,  over  persons,  or  as  a  member 
of  a  corporation,  are  derived  by  him  through  his  mother  and  can- 
not be  transmitted  to  his  children  but  devolve  upon  his  sister's 
children. 

As  an  example  of  a  very  thorough  system  of  matrilineal  succes- 
sion we  may  consider  the  taravad  of  the  Nayar  caste  of  Malabar. 
A  taravad  is  an  incorporated  matrilineal  lineage.  It  includes  all 
living  descendants  in  the  female  line  of  an  original  ancestress. 
It  has  therefore  both  male  and  female  members,  all  of  whom  are 


PATRILINEAL   AND    MATRILINEAL   SUCCESSION  37 

children  of  female  members  of  the  group.  It  is  constituted  as  a 
corporation  (a  joint-family  in  the  terminology  of  Indian  lawyers) 
by  the  possession  of  an  estate  which  includes  in  the  first  instance 
possession  of  a  house  or  houses  and  land,  and  in  the  second  place 
rights  over  the  persons  of  its  members.  The  control  of  the  estate 
is  in  the  hands  of  a  'manager'  who  is  normally  the  oldest  male 
member  of  the  group.  In  order  that  the  group  may  retain  complete 
and  exclusive  possession  of  the  children  born  to  its  female  members 
the  Nayars  have  established  a  system  which  denies  all  legal  rights 
to  a  male  parent.  A  Nayar  girl  is  'married'  while  still  very  young 
to  a  suitable  bridegroom  by  the  Hindu  religious  ceremony  of 
the  tying  of  a  jewel.  (It  is  probable  that  in  former  times  the 
'bridegroom'  ceremoniously  deflowered  the  virgin  'bride'.)  On 
the  third  day  the  newly-w^edded  pair  are  divorced  by  the  Hindu 
ceremony  of  dividing  a  piece  of  cloth.  Thereafter  the  divorced 
bridegroom  has  no  rights  over  the  person,  the  estate  or  the  children 
of  his  bride.  At  a  later  period  the  girl  takes  a  lover.  In  former  times, 
amongst  some  of  the  Nayar,  if  not  generally,  a  woman  was  per-  / 
mitted  by  custom  to  have  two  or  more  lovers  at  the  same  time.  / 
As  the  lover  is  not  married  to  the  woman  he  also  has  no  legal  -j 
claims  over  her  person  or  estate  or  over  any  children  that  may 
be  born  of  the  union. 

The  Nayar  system  is  the  most  thoroughgoing  example  of 
perpetual  matrilineal  succession.  The  lineage  group  maintains 
its  continuity  and  its  unity  by  not  admitting  any  outside  person 
to  any  share  in  its  estate.  It  retains  possession  of  its  own  women 
and  claims  exclusive  rights  over  the  children  born  to  them. 

The  status^  of  an  individual  at  a  given  moment  of  time  may 
be  defined  as  the  totality  of  all  his  rights  and  duties  as  recognised 
in  the  social  usages  (laws  and  customs)  of  the  society  to  which  he 
belongs.  The  rights  constituting  a  status,  and  similarly  the  duties, 
are  of  many  different  kinds,  some  relating  to  'the  world  at  large', 
to  the  society  as  a  w-hole,  others  relating  to  some  definite  social 
group  of  which  the  individual  is  a  member  (e.g.  a  man's  rights 
over  and  duties  towards  his  ow^n  clan),  or  to  some  group  of  which 
he  is  not  a  member  but  to  which  he  stands  in  a  special  rela- 
tion (e.g.  a  man's  relation  to  his  mother's  clan  in  a  patrilineal 
clan  system,  or  to  his  father's  clan  in  a  matrilineal  system),  and 

^  It  is  well  always  to  remember  that  status,  estate,  state,  and  the  French  etat 
are  all  different  forms  of  one  and  the  same  word,  the  late  Latin  estatus. 


38  STRUCTURE   AND    FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

yet  others  concern  his  special  relations  as  an  individual  with 
other  individuals. 

Everywhere  in  human  society  the  status  of  an  individual  is 
very  largely  determined  by  birth  as  the  child  of  a  particular  father 
and  particular  mother.  Behind  the  question  of  succession,  there- 
fore, lies  the  question  of  what  elements  of  status,  i.e.  what  rights 
and  duties,  are  transmitted  to  the  child  by  the  father  on  the  one 
hand  and  by  the  mother  on  the  other.  Every  society  has  to  establish 
its  system  of  rules  in  this  matter  and  there  is  an  immense  diversity 
of  systems  to  be  found  in  surviving  and  historic  communities.  The 
almost  universal  rule  is  that  an  individual  derives  some  elements 
of  his  status  from  or  through  his  father,  and  others  from  or  through 
his  mother. 

It  has  to  be  remembered  that  in  all  societies  there  is  a  general 
difference  between  the  status  of  a  man  and  that  of  a  woman, 
and  in  some  societies  these  differences  are  very  marked  and  very 
important.  Thus  when  a  son  'succeeds'  his  father  he  may  attain 
a  status  very  similar  to  that  of  his  father,  but  a  daughter  cannot  do 
so  to  the  same  extent.  The  reverse  holds  true  in  the  instance  of 
a  mother  and  her  daughter  on  the  one  hand  and  her  son  on  the 
other.  Thus  in  African  kingdoms  w^here  succession  is  matrilineal  a 
king  is  succeeded  by  his  younger  brother  and  then  by  his  sister's 
son.  The  heir  therefore  acquires,  through  his  mother,  important 
elements  of  the  status  of  his  mother's  brother.  The  king's  sister, 
who  holds  a  very  important  position,  is,  of  course,  succeeded 
by  her  daughter. 

One  solution  of  the  problem  of  the  determination  of  status 
would  be  to  let  the  sons  derive  from  the  father  and  daughters 
from  the  mother.  This  principle  is  only  known  to  be  adopted  in  a 
few  tribes,  about  which  we  know  very  little,  in  East  Africa  and  in 
New  Britain.  As  a  working  arrangement  it  has  weighty  objections 
which  cannot  be  gone  into  here. 

It  is  possible  to  have  a  system  in  which  a  child,  by  birth, 
acquires  the  same  rights,  of  the  same  kind  and  to  an  equal  degree, 
over  the  persons  to  whom  he  is  related  through  his  father  and  those 
to  whom  he  is  related  through  his  mother.  An  instance  of  this  is 
that  where  a  person  has  an  equal  expectation  of  testamentary  or 
intestate  succession  to  the  estate  of  the  brothers  and  sisters  of 
his  father  and  those  of  his  mother.  A  further  instance  is  provided 
by  the  customs  relating  to  wergild  amongst  the  Teutonic  peoples. 


PATRILINEAL   AND   MATRILINEAL   SUCCESSION  39 

By  birth  a  man  acquired  rights  over  a  number  of  persons  who 
constituted  his  sib.^  This  included  all  his  relatives  through 
his  father  and  through  his  mother,  counting  either  through  males 
or  through  females,  within  a  certain  range.  This  range  varied 
in  different  Teutonic  communities  and  perhaps  in  the  same  com- 
munity at  different  times.  Amongst  some  of  the  Anglo-Saxons  it 
extended  as  far  as  fifth  cousins.  If  a  man  were  killed  all  the  members 
of  his  sib  could  claim  a  share  in  the  indemnity  (wergild)  paid  by  the 
killer,  proportionate  to  the  degree  of  the  relationship.  Inversely, 
if  a  man  killed  another  all  members  of  his  sib  were  under  obligation 
to  contribute  to  the  blood-money  he  had  to  pay,  each  contributing 
in  the  same  proportion  as  he  would  receive  if  the  man  himself 
had  been  killed.  The  members  of  a  man's  sib  had  specific  rights 
in  rem  in  relation  to  him  and  specific  duties  in  personam  towards 
him. 

The  solution  adopted  by  the  great  majority  of  human  societies 
of  the  problem  relating  to  the  determination  of  status  has  been 
one  by  which  a  child  derives  certain  rights  and  duties  through 
the  father  and  others  of  a  different  kind  through  the  mother.  Where 
the  rights  and  duties  derived  through  the  father  preponderate 
in  social  importance  over  those  derived  through  the  mother  we 
have  what  it  is  usual  to  call  a  patrilineal  system.  Inversely  a 
matrilineal  system  is  one  in  which  the  rights  and  duties  derived 
through  the  mother  preponderate  over  those  derived  through  the 
father. 

There  are,  however,  some  societies  in  which  there  is  a  fairly 
even  balance  between  the  elements  of  status  derived  through  the 
father  and  those  through  the  mother.  An  example  is  provided 
by  the  OvaHerero  of  south-west  Africa.  Through  his  mother  a 
child  derives  membership  in  an  eanda,  a  matrilineal  clan;  through 
his  father  he  becomes  a  member  of  an  oruzo,  a  patrilineal  clan. 
There  is  thus  a  double  system  of  clans  crossing  one  another. 
As  both  kinds  of  clans  are  exogamous  a  man  cannot  belong  to  the 
eanda  of  his  father  or  to  the  onizo  of  his  mother.  Through  his 
mother  and  as  a  member  of  her  eanda  he  has  certain  rights  over, 
and   duties  towards,  that  group   and   particularly  his  mother's 

^  Professor  Lowie  and  some  American  writers  use  the  term  'sib'  as  equivalent 
to  what  is  here,  in  accordance  with  European  usage,  called  a  'clan'.  It  seems 
desirable  to  retain  the  word  'sib'  for  the  bilateral  group  of  kindred  to  which  it 
was  originally  applied. 


40  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

l^rothers  and  his  sister's  children.  Secular  property  is  inherited 
only  within  the  eanda  so  that  a  man  inherits  such  property  from 
his  mother's  brother  and  transmits  it  to  his  sister's  son.  On  the 
other  hand  through  his  father  and  as  a  member  of  his  oruzo  he 
has  rights  and  duties  of  other  kinds  in  relation  to  that  group. 
Certain  sacred  cattle  may  only  be  inherited  within  the  onizo  and 
are  therefore  transmitted  from  father  to  son. 

There  are  to  be  found  in  Africa  and  in  Oceania  other  in- 
stances of  systems  in  which  patrilineal  and  matrilineal  succession 
are  combined  and  more  or  less  balanced  against  one  another.  In 
a  considerable  part  of  Africa  this  is  rationalised  by  a  conception 
that  every  human  being  is  compounded  of  two  principles,  one, 
called  the  'blood'  in  Ashanti,  derived  from  the  mother,  the  other, 
the  'spirit',  derived  from  the  father. 

Probably  the  most  important  factor  in  determining  the  nature 
of  succession  in  the  simpler  societies  is  the  need  of  defining 
rights  i7i  rem  over  persons.  When  a  child  is  born  there  is  the 
question,  'To  whom  does  the  child  belong?'  It  may,  of  course,  be 
regarded  as  belonging  jointly  to  the  two  parents.  Both  have  an 
interest  in  it,  both  have  rights  in  personam  and  ifi  rem  in  relation 
to  it.  But  there  are  other  persons  who  have  rights,  in  personam  and 
i?i  rem  over  the  father  (his  parents,  and  brothers  and  sisters)  and 
others  who  similarly  have  rights  over  the  mother.  In  any  society 
in  which  kinship  is  of  fundamental  importance  in  the  total  social 
structure,  as  it  is  in  the  majority  of  non-European  societies,  it  is 
essential  for  social  stability  and  continuity  that  the  rights  of 
different  individuals  over  a  given  individual  should  be  defined  in 
such  a  way  as  to  avoid  as  far  as  possible  conflicts  of  rights.  We 
have  seen  how  the  ancient  Teutonic  system  gives  similar,  and  in 
some  instances  equal,  rights  in  rem  to  the  father's  kin  and  to  the 
mother's  kin  of  a  given  individual  so  that  if  he  is  killed  all  members 
of  liis  sib  (i.e.  liis  kindred  on  both  sides)  are  entitled  to  compen- 
sation. Let  us  now  consider  examples  of  the  solution  of  this  prob- 
lem in  matrilineal  and  patrilineal  systems. 

For  a  matrilineal  system  we  may  return  to  the  Nayar  as 
affording  an  extreme,  and  therefore  crucial  instance.  In  that 
system  the  taravad,  or  joint-family,  maintains  intact  and  absolute 
its  rights  in  rem  over  all  its  members.  Marriage  normally  gives  the 
husband  certain  rights  in  rem  over  his  wife  and  over  the  children. 
The  Nayars  may  be  said  either  to  have  eliminated  marriage  or  to 


PATRILINEAL   AND   MATRILINEAL   SUCCESSION  4I 

have  eliminated  this  aspect  of  marriage.  It  is  true  that  the  union 
of  a  Nayar  woman  and  her  samhatidham  lover  is  often  a  life-long 
union  of  great  affection  and  that  the  lover  has  a  great  attachment 
to  the  children.  But  legally  he  has  no  rights  over  his  'wife',  if 
we  call  her  such,  or  over  the  children.  In  turn  the  group  has  no 
rights  in  rem  over  him  for  these  remain  with  his  own  taravad. 
The  taravad  as  a  corporation  retains  undivided  and  undisputed 
possession  of  its  own  estate. 

As  an  instance  of  a  definitely  patrilineal  solution  of  the  problem 
of  the  distribution  of  rights  in  rem  we  may  take  the  Zulu-Kaffir 
tribes  of  South  Africa.  In  these  tribes  marriage  requires  the 
payment  of  an  indemnity  in  the  form  of  a  number  of  cattle, 
called  the  Ikazi,  the  act  of  transfer  of  these  being  known  as 
iiku-lobola.  An  unmarried  girl  belongs  to  her  father,  or  to  her 
guardian  (father's  brother  or  brother)  if  her  father  be  dead,  and 
to  her  agnatic  kindred.  They  have  over  her  certain  rights  in 
perso7iam  and  m  rem.  An  offence  committed  against  her,  as  rape, 
seduction,  maiming  or  homicide,  is  an  injury  to  her  kin  and  they 
have  the  right  to  be  indemnified.  A  father  may  bring  before  the 
chief  an  action  for  compensation  for  an  offence  committed  against 
his  daughter.  By  the  act  of  marriage  the  father  and  the  agnatic 
kindred  surrender  a  great  part  of  these  rights  over  the  daughter 
to  her  husband  and  to  his  agnatic  kindred.  The  payment  of  cattle 
is  an  indemnification  for  this  surrender  of  rights.  For  these 
people  the  great  value  of  a  woman  is  as  the  mother  of  children. 
(For  this  reason  there  is  no  more  unhappy,  unwanted  person 
among  them  than  a  barren  woman.)  The  act  of  lobola  is  therefore 
primarily  a  procedure  whereby  those  paying  the  cattle  acquire 
undivided  and  indisputable  rights  over  all  children  born  to  the 
woman.  This  is  readily  demonstrated  by  an  analysis  that  would 
be  out  of  place  here.  The  natives  state  the  principle  in  two  ways: 
'Cattle  beget  children';  'The  children  are  where  the  cattle  are  not.' 
In  case  of  divorce  either  the  wife  and  her  children  return  to  her 
father  and  any  cattle  paid  are  returned,  or  if  (as  is  usual)  the  husband 
retains  the  children  he  must  abandon  claim  to  the  cattle  he  has 
paid  or  to  some  portion  thereof.  On  the  death  of  a  wife  who  has 
borne  children  (a  barren  wife  may  be  repudiated  and  the  re- 
payment of  the  cattle  or  the  substitution  of  a  sister  may  be  claimed) 
if  all  the  cattle  have  been  paid,  the  children  remain  with  the  father 
and  the  mother's  kin  have  no  rights  in  rem  over  them.  The  system 


42  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

here  outlined  is  a  simple  legal  procedure  for  giving  the  father  and 
his  agnatic  kindred  indisputable  and  undivided  rights  in  rem 
over  his  children. 

VThus  the  system  of  patrilineal  or  matrilineal  succession 
cemfeTTargely  around  the  system  of  marriage.  In  an  extreme 
matrilineal  society  a  man  has  no  rights  in  rem  over  his  children, 
though  he  does  usually  have  certain  rights  in  personam.  The 
rights  remain  with  the  mother  and  her  relatives.  The  result  is  to 
emphasise  and  maintain  a  close  bond  between  brother  and  sister 

i    at  the  expense  of  the  bond  between  husband  and  wife.  Con- 

(  sequently  the  rights  of  the  husband  over  his  wife  are  limited. 
In  an  extreme  patrilineal  society  we  have  exactly  the  opposite. 
Rights  in  rem  over  the  children  are  exclusively  exercised  by  the 
father  and  his  relatives.  The  bond  between  husband  and  wife  is 
strengthened  at  the  expense  of  the  bond  between  brother  and 
sister.  The  rights  of  the  husbajid  over  his  wife  are  considerable; 

j     she  is  in  manu,  under  his  potestasl 

I  Extreme    patrilineal    systems^  are    comparatively    rare,    and 

extreme  matrilineal  systems  perhaps  even  rarer.  Generally  there 
is  some  modification  by  which,  while  the  kindred  on  the  one  side 
have  a  preponderant  right,  some  rights  are  recognised  on  the  other 
side  also.  Thus  in  the  Cherokee  tribe  of  North  American  Indians, 
while  a  man  belonged  to  his  mother's  clan,  so  that  if  he  were 
killed  they  and  they  alone  would  demand  satisfaction,  yet  he  stood 
in  a  very  special  relation  to  his  father  and  to  his  father's  clan. 

Little  has  been  said  so  far  about  the  inheritance  of  property. 
This  is  because  in  the  simpler  societies  the  transmission  of  property 
is  generally  dependent  upon  the  transmission  of  status.  Thus 
amongst  the  Nayar  the  important  property  (land,  houses,  etc.)  is 
the  undivided  or  joint  possession  of  a  corporation  constituted  by  a 
matrilineal  lineage.  Amongst  the  Zulu- Kaffir  tribes  the  sons  suc- 
ceed to  a  share  of  the  father's  estate  to  the  exclusion  of  daughters 
y  and  their  descendants.  In  general,  though  there  are  a  few  excep- 
tions, it  may  be  said  that  the  transmission  of  property  follows  the 
same  line  as  does  the  transmission  of  status. 

With  regard  to  the  institutions  of  patrilineal  and  matrilineal 
succession  the  question  is  frequently  asked  as  to  what  is  their 
origin.  The  term  'origin'  is  ambiguous.  In  one  sense  we  may  talk 
of  the  'historical  origin'.  The  historical  origin  of  the  Nayar  system, 
or  that  of  the  Zulu- Kaffirs,  or  of  any  other  system,  is  a  series  of 


PATRILINEAL  AND   MATRILINEAL   SUCCESSION  43 

unique  events  extending  often  over  a  long  period  of  gradual 
growth.  The  determination  of  the  origin  in  this  sense  of  any  social 
system  is  the  task  of  a  historian.  For  the  simpler  peoples  these 
histories  are  unknown  and  are  the  subject  only  of  pure  speculation, 
to  my  mind  largely  unprofitable.  But  the  term  'origin'  may  be 
used  in  another  sense,  and  very  frequently  it  is  used  ambiguously 
with.  a.  confusion  of  the  two  meanings.  "^- 

Any  social  system,  to  survive,  must  conform  to  certain  con- 
ditions. If  we  can  define  adequately  one  of  these  universal 
conditions,  i.e.  one  to  which  all  human  societies  must  conform,  we 
have  a  sociological  law.  Thereupon  if  it  can  be  shown  that  a 
particular  institution  in  a  particular  society  is  the  means  by  which 
that  society  conforms  to  the  law,  i.e.  to  the  necessary  condition, 
we  may  speak  of  this  as  the  '  sociological  origin'  of  the  institution. 
Thus  an  institution  may  be  said  to  have  its  general  raison  d'etre 
(sociological  origin)  and  its  particular  raison  d'etre  (historical 
origin).  The  first  is  for  the  sociologist  or  social  anthropologist 
to  discover  by  the  comparative  method.  The  second  is  for  the 
historian  to  discover  by  examination  of  records  or  for  the  eth- 
nologist, in  the  absence  of  records,  to  speculate  about.  j^y^ 

One  such  law,  or  necessary  condition  of  continued  existence, 
is  that  of  a  certain  degree  of  functional  consistency  amongst  the 
constituent  parts  of  the  social  system.  Functional  consistency  is  not 
the  same  thing  as  logical  consistency;  the  latter  is  one  special 
form  of  the  former.  Functional  inconsistency  exists  whenever  two 
aspects  of  the  social  system  produce  a  conflict  which  can  only  be 
resolved  by  some  change  in  the  system  itself.  It  is  always  a  question 
of  the  functioning,  i.e.  the  working  of  the  system  as  a  whole. 
Consistency  is  a  relative  matter.  No  social  system  ever  attains  to 
a  perfect  consistency,  and  it  is  for  this  reason  that  every  system 
is  constantly  undergoing  change.  Any  insufficiency  in  this  respect 
in  a  social  system  tends  to  induce  change,  sometimes,  though  by 
no  means  always,  through  the  conscious  recognition  of  the 
insufficiency  by  members  of  the  society'  and  the  conscious  seeking 
of  a  remedy.  To  this  law  of  the  necessity  of  a  certain  degree  of  func- 
tional consistency  we  may  add  a  second,  which  is  a  special  instance 
of  the  first.  Any  human  social  life  requires  the  establishment  of 
a  social  structure  consisting  of  a  network  of  relations  between 
individuals  and  groups  of  individuals.  These  relations  all  involve 
certain  rights  and  duties  which  need  to  be  defined  in  such  a  way 


44  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

that  conflicts  of  rights  can  be  resolved  without  destroying  the 
structure.  It  is  this  need  that  is  met  by  the  establishment  of 
systems  of  justice  and  legal  institutions. 

Every  system  of  rights  necessarily  involves  the  existence  of 
common,  joint  or  divided  rights  over  the  same  person  or  thing. 
The  father  and  the  mother  of  a  child  both  have  rights  in  personam 
over  their  child.  In  an  orderly  family  it  is  necessary  that  there  should 
be  no  unresolved  or  unresolvable  conflict  between  these  rights. 
The  same  thing  is  true  throughout  a  society  as  a  whole  in  all  the 
various  relations  into  which  persons  are  brought.  When  two 
persons  A  and  B  have  rights  over  something  Z  or  rights  in  rem 
over  some  person  Z,  there  are  three  ways  of  adjusting  these  rights 
so  as  to  avoid  unresolvable  conflicts.  One  is  the  mode  of  rights  in 
common  ;  A  and  B  have  similar  and  equal  rights  over  Z  and  these 
are  such  that  the  rights  of  A  will  not  conflict  with  those  of  B. 
An  instance  is  to  be  found  in  the  native  tribes  of  South  Africa  in 
which,  as  the  native  saying  is,  'grass  and  water  are  common'. 
Any  member  of  a  tribe  has  the  right  to  graze  his  cattle  or  water 
them,  or  take  water  for  his  own  use,  in  any  part  of  the  territory 
over  which  the  tribe  (represented  by  its  chief)  exercises  dominion. 
A  second  is  the  mode  of  joint  rights  in  which  A  and  B  (or  any 
number  of  persons)  exercise  jointly  certain  rights  over  Z.  The 
establishment  of  such  joint  rights  immediately  establishes  what  is 
here  called  a  corporation.  An  infringement  of  the  rights  normally 
calls  for  a  joint  action  on  the  part  of  the  corporation,  which  may, 
of  course,  be  carried  out  by  its  official  representatives.  A  South 
African  tribe  has  joint  possession  of  its  territory,  the  possession 
(the  estate)  being  vested  in  the  chief.  An  infringement  of  these 
rights  may  be  adjusted  by  the  chief  or  may  lead  to  the  action  of 
war,  in  which,  under  the  chief,  the  whole  tribe  seeks  to  maintain 
its  rights.  The  third  mode  is  that  of  rights  in  division.  Here  A  has 
certain  definite  rights  over  Z  and  B  has  certain  other  definite 
rights;  the  respective  rights  may  be  defined  either  by  custom  or  by 
a  specific  contract,  or  agreement.  An  example  is  the  relation  of 
owner  and  tenant  of  a  leased  land  or  building. 

So  far  as  rights  over  persons  go  the  exercise  of  rights  in 
common  is  necessarily  very  limited.  In  an  unfamiliar  region  one 
may  ask  direction  from  any  person  one  meets  and  expect  to  receive 
whatever  information  that  person  can  give.  In  English  law  the 
king's  officers  can  demand  from  any  passer-by  'in  the  king's  name' 


PATRILINEAL   AND   MATRILINEAL   SUCCESSION  45 

assistance  in  the  arrest  of  a  malefactor.^  Rights  over  persons 
in  personam  are  usually  exercised  either  jointly  or  in  division. 

Rights  over  persons  in  rem  can  obviously  never  be  exercised 
in  common.  We  have  seen,  from  the  example  of  the  Teutonic 
customs  relating  to  wergild,  that  they  can  be  held  in  division.  But 
such  a  thing  is  rare  and  for  the  reason  that  it  requires  a  compli- 
cated definition  of  the  respective  shares  of  various  kindred  in 
their  interest  in  their  kinsmen.  One  has  only  to  glance  at  some 
of  the  early  laws  of  Norway  and  Sweden  relating  to  the  division  of 
the  wergild  between  agnatic  and  cognatic  kin  of  different  degrees 
to  realise  with  what  difficulties  such  a  system  is  confronted  in  its 
working. 

It  results  from  this  that  rights  in  rem  over  a  person  must 
as  a  general  rule  either  be  exclusively  personal,  i.e.  confined  to  a 
single  individual  (a  condition  to  which  the  rights  of  an  owner 
over  a  slave  may  approximate  in  some  instances)  or  must  be 
joint.  The  rights  of  a  Roman  father  over  his  children  were  nearly 
exclusive  but  even  these,  at  certain  periods  of  history  certainly, 
were  subject  to  the  rights,  exercised  jointly,  of  the  gens  or  of  the 
state;  even  the  potestas  of  a  pater  familias  was  not  absolute.  Thus 
we  may  say  that  any  society  that  recognises  rights  in  rem  over 
persons  (and  all  known  societies  do  so  to  some  extent)  will 
normally,  and  with  only  the  rarest  exceptions,  make  some  provision 
for  the  joint  exercise  of  such  rights.  This  implies  the  existence 
of  corporations  of  some  kind,  since  a  corporation  is  here  defined  as 
a  collection  of  persons  who  jointly  exercise  some  right  or  rights. 

A  corporation  can  only  form  itself  on  the  basis  of  a  common 
interest.  In  the  simplest  societies  the  easiest,  perhaps  almost  the 
only,  ways  in  which  common  interests  can  be  created  are  on 
the  basis  of  locality,  i.e.  residence  in  the  same  local  community 
or  neighbourhood,  or  kinship.  Corporations  therefore  tend  to  be 
established  either  on  the  one  basis  or  the  other  or  on  both  combined 
(the  Kariera  horde  is  an  example  of  the  latter)  or  else  a  double 
system  of  local  groups  and  kinship  groups  is  formed. 

We  must  here  appeal  to  another  sociological  law,  the  necessity  v' 
not  merely  for  stability,  definiteness  and  consistency  in  the  social 
structure,  but  also  for  continuity.  To  provide  continuity  of  social 

^  The  latter  instance,  however,  might  be  interpreted  as  the  exercise  of  a 
joint  right,  since  the  king  is  the  representative  of  the  nation  which,  as  a  cor- 
poration, has  joint  rights  over  the  persons  of  its  citizens. 


46  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

Structure  is  essentially  a  function  of  corporations.  Thus  a  modern 
nation  has  its  continuity  as  a  corporation  exercising  joint  rights 
over  its  territory  and  over  the  persons  of  its  citizens. 

We  can  imagine  as  a  possibility  an  incorporated  local  com- 
munity which  was  completely  endogamous  and  which  would 
therefore  not  have  to  face  the  issue  of  choosing  between  matrilineal 
and  patrilineal  succession,  since  any  child  born  in  the  community 
would  have  both  its  parents  there.  But  the  moment  there  are 
intermarriages  between  two  corporate  local  groups  the  question  of 
lineal  succession  does  arise.  In  such  a  situation  it  is  possible  that 
no  customary  rule  may  be  established,  each  instance  being  ad- 
justed by  agreement  of  the  persons  most  nearly  concerned.  It  seems 
that  this  was  the  case  of  the  hordes  or  local  groups  of  the  Andaman 
Islanders.  The  result  is  to  produce  a  loose  and  indefinite  structure. 
If  any  definite  rule  does  arise  it  must  usually  take  the  form  of  one 
either  of  matrilineal  or  of  patrilineal  succession. 

If  any  society  establishes  a  system  of  corporations  on  the  basis 
of  kinship — clans,  joint-families,  incorporated  lineages — it  must 
necessarily  adopt  a  system  of  unilineal  reckoning  of  succession. 
It  would,  of  course,  be  theoretically  possible  to  establish  some  sort 
of  rule  whereby,  when  the  parents  belong  to  diff"erent  groups,  in 
certain  definite  circumstances  the  children  belong  to  the  father's 
group  and  in  others  to  the  mother's.  This  would  produce  com- 
plicated conditions,  and  in  general  any  complicated  definition  of 
rights  is  likely  to  be  functionally  inefficient  as  compared  with  a 
simpler  one. 

Thus  the  existence  of  unilineal  (patrilineal  or  matrilineal) 
succession  in  the  great  majority  of  human  societies  can  be  traced 
to  its  sociological  'cause'  or  'origin'  in  certain  fundamental 
social  necessities.  Chief  amongst  them,  I  have  suggested,  is  the 
need  of  defining,  with  sufficient  precision  to  avoid  unresolvable 
conflicts,  the  rights  in  rem  over  persons.  The  need  of  precise 
definition  of  rights  in  personam  and  of  rights  over  things  would 
seem  to  be  secondary  but  still  important  factors. 

There  are  many  facts  which  might  be  adduced  to  support  this 
hypothesis.  I  will  mention  only  one  kind.  In  societies  organised 
on  the  basis  of  clans  one  of  the  most  important  activities  of  the 
clan  is  to  exact  vengeance  or  indemnification  when  a  clansman  is 
killed.  The  list  of  known  instances  of  this  would  fill  many  pages. 
The  clan  as  a  corporation  has  rights  in  rem  over  all  its  clansmen. 


PATRILINEAL   AND   MATRILINEAL   SUCCESSION  47 

If  one  is  killed  the  clan  is  injured  and  it  has  the  right,  and  its 
members  are  under  an  obligation,  to  proceed  to  some  action 
towards  receiving  satisfaction,  either  through  vengeance  or  by 
receiving  an  indemnity. 

Thus  the  cause  of  the  decay  of  the  clan  (the  genos  or  gens) 
in  ancient  Greece  and  Rome  was  the  transfer  of  its  rights  in  rem 
(and  necessarily  therefore  of  some  of  its  rights  in  personam )  to 
the  city  or  state,  the  nature  of  these  rights  being  inevitably 
considerably  modified  in  the  process  of  transference.  But  the 
decay  of  the  gens  in  Rome  still  left  the  patriarchal  family  as  a 
corporation  (as  Maine  long  ago  pointed  out)  the  basis  of  which, 
however,  was  not  merely  the  exercise  of  rights  in  rem  by  the  pater 
familias  over  his  children,  but  also  the  exercise  of  joint  rights 
over  property  and  the  maintenance  of  a  religious  cult  of  ancestor- 
worship. 

/The  sociological  laws,  i.e.  the  necessary  conditions  of  exist-    / 
ence  of  a  society,  that  have  here  been  suggested  as  underlying  the 
customs  of  unilineal  (patrilineal  or  matrilineal)  succession  are: 

1.  The  need  for  a  formulation  of  rights  over  persons  and 
things  sufficiently  precise  in  their  general  recognition  as 
to  avoid  as  far  as  possible  unresolved  conflicts. 

2.  The  need  for  continuity  of  the  social  structure  as  a  system 
of  relations  between  persons,  such  relations  being  de- 
finable in  terms  of  rights  and  dutiesTI 

By  American  ethnologists  who  object  to  the  method  of 
explanation  adopted  in  the  preceding  argument  it  is  said  that  any 
sociological  laws  that  can  be  formulated  must  necessarily  be 
truisms.  The  laws  formulated  above,  if  they  be  true,  as  I  believe, 
even  if  not  adequately  expressed,  may  be  truisms.  But  even  so 
they  would  seem  to  need  to  be  brought  to  the  attention  of  at  least 
some  ethnologists.  A  recent  writer  on  the  subject  of  matrilineal 
and  patrilineal  succession^  makes  the  following  statements  : 
'Unilateral  institutions  are  in  themselves  anomalous  and  artificial. 
Matrilineal  ones  are  doubly  so.'  'Unilateral  institutions,  wherever 
found,  represent  deviations  from  the  expectable,  abnormalities 
in  the  social  structure.'  'Unilateral  reckoning  contradicts  the 
duality  of  parenthood  and  results  in  an  unnatural  stressing  of  one 

^  Ronald  L.  Olson,  'Clan  and  Moiety  in  North  America',  University  of 
California  Publications,  Vol.  33,  pp.  409,  411. 


48  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

side  of  the  family  to  the  exclusion  of  the  other.'  On  the  basis  of 
these  assertions  he  seems  to  conclude  that  unilineal  determination 
of  status  must  have  had  a  single  origin  in  some  one  aberrant  people 
and  to  have  spread  from  them,  by  a  process  of  'diffusion',  to  vast 
numbers  of  peoples  in  Europe,  Asia,  Africa,  Austraha,  Oceania 
and  America.  (One  wonders,  of  course,  why  so  many  societies 
of  so  many  different  types  should  have  accepted  and  retained 
such  'anomalous',  'abnormal'  and  'unnatural'  institutions.) 

I  hope  that  the  argument  of  this  paper  has  shown,  on  the 
contrary,  that  unilineal  institutions  in  some  form,  are  almost,  if 
not  entirely,  a  necessity  in  any  ordered  social  system.  What  is 
therefore  unusual  or  rare  (we  need  not  say  abnormal  or  anomalous 
and  still  less  unnatural)  is  the  discovery  of  a  people  such  as  the 
Teutonic  peoples  of  Europe  (apparently  alone  amongst  Indo- 
European  speaking  peoples)  maintaining  for  some  period,  until 
the  coming  of  feudalism  and  Roman  law,  a  system  in  which  there 
is  considerable,  if  not  quite  complete,  avoidance  of  the  unilineal 
principle,  in  which  a  person  derives  similar  and  equal  rights 
through  the  father  and  through  the  mother.^ 

It  might  well  be  expected  that  such  a  paper  as  this  would  deal 
with  the  question  of  what  general  factors  determine  the  selection 
by  some  people  of  the  matrilineal  and  by  others  of  the  patrilineal 
principle  in  determining  status  or  succession.  My  opinion  is  that 
our  knowledge  and  understanding  are  not  sufficient  to  permit  us 
to  deal  with  this  problem  in  any  satisfactory  manner. 

^  There  are  systems  of  bilateral  kinship  with  succession  through  both  males 
and  females  in  some  parts  of  Indonesia,  e.g.  in  the  Ifugao  of  the  Philippine 
Islands.  The  discussion  of  these  would  be  complex  and  require  space  that  is 
not  available. 


CHAPTER     III 

THE   STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  ^ 

FOR  seventy-five  years  the  subject  of  kinship  has  occupied 
a  special  and  important  position  in  social  anthropology. 
I  propose  in  this  address  to  consider  the  methods  that  have 
been  and  are  being  used  in  that  branch  of  our  studies  and  the 
kinds  of  results  that  we  may  reasonably  expect  to  arrive  at  by 
those  methods/l'  shall  consider  and  compare  two  methods  which 
I  shall  speak  of  a&4h^t  of  conjectural  history  and  that  of  structural 
or  sociological  analysisTl 

One  of  these  methods  was  first  applied  to  some  social  in- 
stitutions by  French  and  British  (mostly  Scots)  writers  of  the 
eighteenth  century.  It  was  of  this  method  that  Dugald  Stewart 
wrote  in  1795:  iTo  this  species  of  philosophical  investigation, 
which  has  no  appropriated  name  in  our  language,  I  shall  take 
the  liberty  of  giving  the  title  of  Theoretical  or  Conjectural  History; 
an  expression  which  coincides  pretty  nearly  in  its  meaning  with 
that  of  Natural  History,  as  employed  by  Mr.  Hume  (see  his 
Natural  History  of  Religiofi),  and  with  what  some  French  writers 
have  called  Histoire  Raisonnee.'  I  shall  accept  Dugald  Stewart's 
suggestion  and  shall  use  the  name  'conjectural  history^' 

The  method  of  conjectural  history  is  used  in  a  ijiimber  of 
different  ways.  One  is  to  attempt  to  base  on  general  considerations, 
on  what  Dugald  Stewart  calls  'known  principles  of  human  nature', 
conjectures  as  to  first  beginnings — of  political  society  (Hobbes), 
of  language  (Adam  Smith),  of  religion  (Tylor),  of  the  family 
(Westermarck),  and  so  on.  Sometimes  an  attempt  is  made  to  deal 
with  the  whole  course  of  development  of  human  society,  as  in 
the  works  of  Morgan,  Father  Schmidt  and  Elliot  Smith.  Some- 
times we  are  offered  a  conjectural  history  of  the  development 
of  a  particular  institution,  as  in  Robertson  Smith's  treatment  of 
sacrifice.  The  special  form  of  the  method  with  which  we  shall 
be  concerned  in  what  follows  is  the  attempt  to  explain  a  particular 
feature  of  one  or  more  social  systems  by  a  hypothesis  as  to  how 
it  came  into  existence. 

^Presidential    Address    to    the    Royal    Anthropological    Institute,     1941. 
Reprinted  from  the  Joiirnal  of  the  Royal  Anthropological  Institute. 

49 


50  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

An  early  example  of  the  method  of  conjectural  history  applied 
to  kinship  is  to  be  found  in  the  essay  on  Primitive  Marriage 
published  by  John  F.  M'Lennan  in  1865.  You  will  remember 
the  two  principal  theses  put  forward  in  that  book:  the  origin  of 
the  custom  of  exogamy  from  marriage  by  capture,  and  the  pro- 
position that  'the  most  ancient  system  in  which  the  idea  of  blood 
relationship  was  embodied  was  a  system  of  kinship  through 
females  only'.  Six  years  later  there  appeared  The  Systems  of 
Consanguinity  and  Affinity  of  Lewis  Morgan,  a  monument  of 
scholarly,  patient  research  in  the  collection  of  data,  to  be  followed 
in  1877  by  his  Ancient  Society,  in  which  he  offered  a  conjectural 
outline  history  of  the  whole  course  of  social  development.  These 
works  of  M'Lennan  and  Morgan  were  followed  by  a  considerable 
mass  of  literature,  which  has  continued  to  be  produced  down  to 
the  present  day,  in  which  the  method  of  conjectural  history  has 
been  applied  in  different  forms  to  various  features  of  kinship 
organisation. 

\  As  I  think  you  know,  I  regard  the  pursuit  of  this  method  as  one 
of  the  chief  obstacles  to  the  development  of  a  scientific  theory  of 
human  society.  But  my  position  has  often  been  misunderstood. 
My  objection  to  conjectural  history  is  not  that  it  is  historical, 
but  that  it  is  conjectural.  History  shows  us  how  certain  events  or 
changes  in  the  past  have  led  to  certain  other  events  or  conditions, 
and  thus  reveals  human  life  in  a  particular  region  of  the  world  as  a 
chain  of  connected  happenings.  But  it  can  do  this  only  when  there 
is  direct  evidence  for  both  the  preceding  and  succeeding  events 
or  conditions  and  also  some  actual  evidence  of  their  interconnection. 
In  conjectural  history  we  have  direct  knowledge  about  a  state  of 
affairs  existing  at  a  certain  time  and  place,  without  any  adequate 
knowledge  of  the  preceding  conditions  and  events,  about  which 
we  are  therefore  reduced  to  making  conjectures.  To  establish  any 
probability  for  such  conjectures  we  should  need  to  have  a  know- 
ledge of  laws  of  social  development  which  we  certainly  do  not 
possess  and  to  which  I  do  not  think  we  shall  ever  attainTj 

My  own  study  of  kinship  began  in  1904  under  "iGvers,  when 
I  was  his  first  and  at  that  time  his  only  student  in  social  anthropo- 
logy, having  for  three  years  previously  studied  psychology  under 
him.  I  owe  a  great  deal  to  that  contact  with  Rivers,  and  more  rather 
than  less  because  from  the  outset  it  appeared  that  we  disagreed 
on  the  subject  of  method.  For  Rivers  followed  the  method  of 


THE  STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  5 1 

conjectural  history,  at  first  under  the  influence  of  Morgan,  and 
later  in  the  form  of  what  he  called  ethnological  analysis,  as 
exemplified  in  his  History  of  Melanesian  Society  (1914a).  But  in 
his  field  work  Rivers  had  discovered  and  revealed  to  others  the 
importance  of  the  investigation  of  the  behaviour  of  relatives  to  one 
another  as  a  means  of  understanding  a  system  of  kinship.  In 
what  follows  I  shall  be  criticising  one  side  of  Rivers'  work,  but 
the  position  I  now  hold  is  the  one  I  held  in  my  friendly  discussions 
with  him  during  a  period  of  ten  years,  ending  in  an  agreement  to 
go  on  disagreeing.  My  esteem  for  Rivers  as  man,  as  teacher,  and 
as  scientist,  is  in  no  way  diminished  by  the  fact  that  I  find  myself 
obliged  to  criticise  adversely  his  use  of  the  method  of  conjectural 
history. 

At  the  outset  it  is  necessary  to  give  a  definition.  I  shall  use  the 
term  'kinship  system'  as  short  for  a  system  of  kinsliip  and  marriage 
or  kinship  and  affinity.  It  is  a  pity  that  there  is  no  inclusive  term 
in  English  for  all  relationships  which  result  from  the  existence 
of  the  family  and  marriage.  It  would  be  very  tiresome  to  speak 
all  the  time  of  a  system  of  kinship  and  affinity.  I  hope,  therefore, 
that  my  use  of  the  term  will  be  accepted.  It  need  not  lead  to 
ambiguity. 

The  unit  of  structure  from  which  a  kinship  system  is  built 
up  is  the  group  which  I  call  an  'elementary  family',  consisting 
of  a  man  and  his  wife  and  their  child  or  children,  whether  they 
are  living  together  or  not.  A  childless  married  couple  does  not 
constitute  a  family  in  this  sense.  Children  may  be  acquired,  and 
thus  made  members  of  an  elementary  family,  by  adoption  as  well 
as  by  birth.  We  must  also  recognise  the  existence  of  compound 
families.  In  a  polygynous  family  there  is  only  one  husband  with 
two  or  more  wives  and  their  respective  children.  Another  form 
of  compound  family  is  produced  in  monogamous  societies  by 
a  second  marriage,  giving  rise  to  what  we  call  step -relationships 
and  such  relationships  as  that  of  half-brothers.  Compound  families 
can  be  regarded  as  formed  of  elementary  families  with  a  common 
member. 

The  existence  of  the  elementary  family  creates  three  special 
kinds  of  social  relationship,  that  between  parent  and  child,  that 
between  children  of  the  same  parents  (siblings),  and  that  between 
husband  and  wife  as  parents  of  the  same  child  or  children.  A 
person  is  born  or  adopted  into  a  family  in  which  he  or  she  is 


52  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

son  or  daughter  and  brother  or  sister.  When  a  man  marries  and 
has  children  he  now  belongs  to  a  second  elementary  family,  in 
which  he  is  husband  and  father.  This  interlocking  of  elementary 
families  creates  a  network  of  what  I  shall  call,  for  lack  of  any  better 
term,  genealogical  relations,  spreading  out  indefinitely. 

The  three  relationships  that  exist  within  the  elementary 
family  constitute  what  I  call  the  first  order.  Relationships 
of  the  second  order  are  those  which  depend  on  the  connection 
of  two  elementary  families  through  a  common  member,  and  are 
such  as  father's  father,  mother's  brother,  wife's  sister,  and  so  on. 
In  the  third  order  are  such  as  father's  brother's  son  and  mother's 
brother's  wife.  Thus  we  can  trace,  if  v/e  have  genealogical  in- 
formation, relationships  of  the  fourth,  fifth  or  nth  order.  In  any 
given  society  a  certain  number  of  these  relationships  are  recog- 
nised for  social  purposes,  i.e.  they  have  attached  to  them  certain 
rights  and  duties,  or  certain  distinctive  modes  of  behaviour.  It  is 
the  relations  that  are  recognised  in  this  way  that  constitute  what 
I  am  calling  a  kinship  system,  or,  in  full,  a  system  of  kinship  and 
affinity. 

A  most  important  character  of  a  kinship  system  is  its  range. 
In  a  narrow  range  system,  such  as  the  English  system  of  the 
present  day,  only  a  limited  number  of  relatives  are  recognised 
as  such  in  any  way  that  entails  any  special  behaviour  or  any 
specific  rights  and  duties.  In  ancient  times  in  England  the  range 
was  wider,  since  a  fifth  cousin  had  a  claim  to  a  share  of  the  wergild 
when  a  man  was  killed.  In  systems  of  very  wide  range,  such  as  are 
found  in  some  non-European  societies,  a  man  may  recognise 
many  hundreds  of  relatives,  towards  each  of  whom  his  behaviour 
is  qualified  by  the  existence  of  the  relationship. 

It  must  be  noted  also  that  in  some  societies  persons  are  re- 
garded as  being  connected  by  relationships  of  the  same  kind 
although  no  actual  genealogical  tie  is  known.  Thus  the  members 
of  a  clan  are  regarded  as  being  kinsmen,  although  for  some  of  them 
it  may  not  be  possible  to  show  their  descent  from  a  common 
ancestor.  It  is  this  that  distinguishes  what  will  here  be  called  a 
clan  from  a  lineage. 

Thus  a  kinship  system,  as  I  am  using  the  term,  or  a  system 
of  kinship  and  affinity  if  you  prefer  so  to  call  it,  is  in  the  first  place 
a  system  of  dyadic  relations  between  person  and  person  in  a 
community,  the  behaviour  of  any  two  persons  in  any  of  these 


THE    STUDY    OF    KINSHIP    SYSTEMS  53 

relations  being  regulated  in  some  way,  and  to  a  greater  or  less 
extent,  by  social  usage. 

A  kinship  system  also  includes  the  existence  of  definite  social- 
groups.  The  first  of  these  is  the  domestic  family,  which  is  a  group 
of  persons  who  at  a  particular  time  are  living  together  in  one 
dwelling,  or  collection  of  dwellings,  with  some  sort  of  economic 
arrangement  that  we  may  call  joint  housekeeping.  There  are  many 
varieties  of  the  domestic  family,  varying  in  their  form,  their  size, 
and  the  manner  of  their  common  life.  A  domestic  family  may 
consist  of  a  single  elementary  family,  or  it  may  be  a  group  in- 
cluding a  hundred  or  more  persons,  such  as  the  zadniga  of  the 
Southern  Slavs  or  the  taravad  of  the  Nayar.  Important  in  some 
societies  is  what  may  be  called  a  local  cluster  of  domestic  families. 
In  many  kinship  systems  unilinear  groups  of  kindred — lineage 
groups,  clans  and  moieties — play  an  important  part. 

By  a  kinship  system,  then,  I  mean  a  network  of  social  relations 
of  the  kind  just  defined,  which  thus  constitutes  part  of  that  total 
network  of  social  relations  that  I  call  social  structure.  The  rights 
and  duties  of  relatives  to  one  another  and  the  social  usages  that 
they  observe  in  their  social  contacts,  since  it  is  by  these  that  the 
relations  are  described,  are  part  of  the  system.  I  regard  ancestor- 
worship,  where  it  exists,  as  in  a  real  sense  part  of  the  kinship 
system,  constituted  as  it  is  by  the  relations  of  living  persons  to  their 
deceased  kindred,  and  afi^ecting  as  it  does  the  relations  of  living 
persons  to  one  another.  The  terms  used  in  a  society  in  addressing 
or  referring  to  relatives  are  a  part  of  the  system,  and  so  are  the 
ideas  that  the  people  themselves  have  about  kinship. 

You  will  perceive  that  by  using  the  word  'system'  I  have  made 
an  assumption,  an  important  and  far-reaching  assumption;  for 
that  word  implies  that  whatever  it  is  applied  to  is  a  complex 
unity,  an  organised  whole^My  explicit  hypothesis  is  that  between 
the  various  features  of  a  particular  kinship  system  there  is  a 
complex  relation  of  interdependence.  The  formulation  of  this 
working  hypothesis  leads  immediately  to  the  method  of  socio- 
logical analysis,  by  which  we  seek  to  discover  ^the  nature  of 
kinship  systems  as  systems,  if  they  be  really  such,,' For  this  pur- 
pose we  need  to  make  a  systematic  comparison  of  a  sufficient 
number  of  sufficiently  diverse  systems.J^e  must  compare  them, 
not  in  reference  to  single,  superficial,  and  therefore  immediately 
observable  characters,  but  as  wholes,  as  systems,  and  in  reference, 


54  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

therefore,  to  general  characters  which  are  only  discovered  in  the 
process  of  comparisoni  Our  purpose  is  to  arrive  at  valid  abstrac- 
tions or  general  ideas  in  terms  of  which  the  phenomena  can  be 
described  and  classified. 

I  propose  to  illustrate  the  two  methods,  that  of  conjectural 
history  and  that  of  system,  analysis,  by  means  of  a  particular 
example,  and  for  this  purpose  I  select  a  peculiar  feature  of  the 
kinship  terminology  of  a  number  of  scattered  tribes.  When  Morgan 
made  his  study  of  the  terminology  of  kinship  in  North  American 
tribes,  he  noted  certain  peculiarities  in  the  terms  for  cousins. 
In  the  Choctaw  tribe  he  found  that  a  man  calls  his  father's  sister's 
son  by  the  same  term  of  relationship  that  he  applies  to  his  own 
father  and  his  father's  brother.  We  may  say  that  the  father's 
sister's  son  is  thus  treated  in  the  terminology  as  though  he  were 
a  younger  brother  of  the  father.  Reciprocally  a  man  calls  his 
mother's  brother's  son  by  the  term  for  'son'.  Consistently  with 
this  he  applies  one  term  of  relationship  to  his  father's  sister 
and  her  daughter,  and  speaks  of  his  mother's  brother's  daughter 
as  a  'daughter'.  In  the  Omaha  tribe,  on  the  other  hand,  Morgan 
found  that  a  man  calls  his  mother's  brother's  son  'uncle',  i.e. 
mother's  brother,  and  calls  his  mother's  brother's  daughter 
'mother',  so  that  reciprocally  he  speaks  of  his  father's  sister's  son 
by  the  term  that  he  uses  for  his  sister's  son,  and  a  woman  uses 
a  single  term  for  her  own  son,  her  sister's  son  and  her  father's 
sister's  son.  Figs,  i  and  2  will  help  to  make  these  terminologies 
clear. 

Terminologies  similar  to  the  Omaha  are  found  in  a  number  of 
regions:  (i)  in  the  Siouan  tribes  related  to  the  Omaha,  such  as 
the  Osage,  Winnebago,  etc.;  (2)  in  certain  Algonquian  tribes,  of 
which  we  may  take  the  Fox  Indians  as  an  example;  (3)  in  an 
area  of  California  which  includes  the  Miwok;  (4)  in  some  tribes  of 
East  Africa,  both  Bantu  and  non-Bantu,  including  the  Nandi  and 
the  BaThonga;  (5)  amongst  the  Lhota  Nagas  of  Assam;  and 
(6)  in  some  New  Guinea  tribes.  Terminologies  similar  to  the 
Choctaw  are  found:  (i)  in  other  south-eastern  tribes  of  the  United 
States,  including  the  Cherokee;  (2)  in  the  Crow  and  Hidatsa 
tribes  of  the  Plains  area;  (3)  amongst  the  Hopi  and  some  other 
Pueblo  Indians;  (4)  in  the  Tlingit  and  Haida  of  the  north-west 
coast  of  America;  (5)  in  the  Banks  Islands  in  Melanesia;  and  (6) 
in  one  Twi-speaking  community  of  West  Africa. 


THE   STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  55 

There  are  some  who  would  regard  this  kind  of  terminology 
as  'contrary  to  common  sense',  but  that  means  no  more  than  that 
it  is  not  in  accordance  with  our  modern  European  ideas  of  kinship 
and  its  terminology.  It  ought  to  be  easy  for  any  anthropologist  to 
recognise  that  what  is  common  sense  in  one  society  may  be  the 


=  O 
Fs 


I 

O 
Fs 


"I     r 

A  =  O 
F 


Ego 


O 


A 
mB 


O 
d 


0 

A 

0 

A 

Fs 

F 

s 

B 

Fig.  I— c 

HOCTAW 

:^o^) 

_ 

=  0 

1 
A 

1           1 
A  =  0 

1 
0 

1 
A  = 

_ 

Fs 

F 

F 

m 

m 

mB 

0 

1 
A 

Ef 

;o 

_ 

1 
=   0 

1 
A  = 

_ 

sd 

sS 

m 

mB 

1 
0 

1 
A 

1 
0 

1 
A 

s 

B 

m 

mB 

Fig.  2 — 

DMAHA 

F 

=  Father 

m  = 

mother 

B 

=  Brother 

d  = 

daught 

2r 

S 

=  Son 

s  = 

sister 

opposite  of  common  sense  in  another.  The  Choctaw  and  Omaha 
terminologies  do  call  for  some  explanation;  but  so  does  the 
English  terminology,  in  which  we  use  the  word  'cousin'  for  all 
children  of  both  brothers  and  sisters  of  both  mother  and  father — 
a  procedure  which  would  probably  seem  to  some  non-Europeans 
to  be  contrary  not  only  to  common  sense  but  also  to  morals.  What 
I  wish  to  attempt,  therefore,  is  to  show  you  that  the  Choctaw 
and  Omaha  terminologies  are  just  as  reasonable  and  fitting  in  the 


56  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SCCItTl 

social  systems  in  which  they  occur  as  our  o\\n  terminology  is 
in  our  own  social  system. 

I  would  point  out  that  the  Choctaw^  system  and  the  Omaha 
system  exhibit  a  single  structural  principle  applied  in  different 
ways,  in  what  we  may  perhaps  call  opposite  directions.  We  shall 
therefore  consider  them  together,  as  varieties  of  a  single  species. 

Attempts  have  been  made  to  explain  these  terminologies  by 
the  method  of  conjectural  history.  The  first  was  that  of  Kohler  in 
1897,  in  his  essay  'Zur  Urgeschichte  der  Ehe',  Kohler  set  out  to 
defend  Morgan's  theory  of  group -marriage,  and  used  the  Choctaw 
and  Omaha  systems  for  his  argument.  He  explained  the  Choctaw 
terminology  as  the  result  of  marriage  with  the  mother's  brother's 
wife,  and  the  Omaha  system  as  the  result  of  a  custom  of  marriage 
w4th  the  wife's  brother's  daughter.  Kohler's  essay  was  reviewed 
by  Durkheim  (1898)  in  what  was  an  important,  if  brief,  con- 
tribution to  the  theory  of  kinship.  He  rejected  Kohler's  hypotheses, 
and  pointed  out  the  connection  of  the  Choctaw  and  Omaha  systems 
with  matrilineal  and  patrilineal  descent  respectively. 

The  subject  was  considered  again  by  Rivers  in  reference  to  the 
Banks  Islands,  and,  without  bringing  in,  as  Kohler  had  done, 
the  question  of  group-marriage,  he  explained  the  Banks  Islands 
terminology  as  resulting  from  a  custom  of  marriage  with  the 
mother's  brother's  widow.  Gifford  (1916),  having  found  the 
characteristic  feature  of  the  Omaha  system  in  the  Miwok  of 
California,  followed  the  lead  of  Kohler  and  Rivers,  and  explained 
it  as  the  result  of  the  custom  of  marriage  with  the  wife's  brother's 
daughter.  About  the  same  time,  and  independently,  Mrs.  Seligman 
(1917)  offered  the  same  explanation  of  the  Omaha  feature  as  it 
occurs  in  the  Nandi  and  other  tribes  of  Africa. 

Let  me  summarise  the  argument  with  reference  to  the  Omaha 
type.  The  hypothesis  is  that  in  certain  societies,  mostly  having 
a  definite  patrilineal  organisation,  a  custom  was  for  some  reason 
adopted  of  permitting  a  man  to  marry  his  wife's  brother's  daughter. 
Referring  to  Fig,  3,  this  means  that  D  would  be  allowed  to 
marry  f.  When  such  a  marriage  occurred,  then  for  G  and  h,  f, 
who  is  their  mother's  brother's  daughter,  would  become  their 
step-mother,  and  E,  their  mother's  brother's  son,  would  become 
the  brother  of  their  step-mother.  The  hypothesis  then  assumes 
that  the  kinship  terminology  was  so  modified  as  to  anticipate  this 
form  of  marriage  wherever  it  might  occur.  G  and  h  will  call  f, 


THE   STUDY    OF    KINSHIP    SYSTEMS 


57 


their  mother's  brother's  daughter  and  therefore  their  possible 
future  step-mother,  'mother',  and  her  brother  E  they  will  call 
'mother's  brother'.  Reciprocally  f  will  call  G  'son'  and  E  will  call 
him  'sister's  son'.  There  is  an  exactly  parallel  argument  for  the 
Choctaw^  system.  A  custom  arises  by  which  a  man  may  occasionally 
marry  the  widow  of  his  mother's  brother.  In  the  figure,  G  would 
marry  b,  the  wife  of  his  mother's  brother  A.  Thus  E  and  f  \vould 
become  his  step-children.  If  this  marriage  is  anticipated  in  the 
terminology,  then  E  and  f  will  call  G  'father'  and  h  'father's 
sister'. 

Let  us  note  that  in  the  Omaha  tribe  and  in  some  others  having 
a  similar  terminolog}'  it  is  regarded  as  permissible  for  a  man  to 
marry  his  wife's  brother's  daughter.  Marriage  with  the  mother's 
brother's  v.idow  does  not  seem  to  occur  regularly  with  the  Choctaw 


A   = 

=   O 

1 

O  = 

_ 

A 

b 

c 

1 
A 

O 

1 
A 

E 

f 

Fig 

3 

G 

Note—A 

and 

c  are 

brc 

ther 

and  sist 

er 

terminology,  and  does  certainly  occur  without  it,  even  in  tribes 
with  an  Omaha  terminology  such  as  the  BaThonga. 

The  basis  of  what  we  may  call  the  Kohler  hypothesis  is  the 
obvious  fact  that  in  each  of  the  two  varieties  the  terminology 
and  the  special  form  of  marriage  are  consistent;  the  two  things 
fit  together  in  what  may  be  called  a  logical  way.  This,  I  think, 
anyone  can  see  by  inspection  of  the  data.  But  the  hypothesis  goes 
far  beyond  this.  It  supposes  that  there  is  some  sort  of  causal 
connection  such  that  the  marriage  custom  can  be  said  to  have 
caused,  produced,  or  resulted  in,  the  special  terminology.  No 
evidence  is  adduced  that  this  is  actually  the  way  in  \\hich  things 
happened.  The  argument  is  entirely  a  priori.  It  is  the  essential 
weakness  of  conjectural  history  that  its  hypotheses  cannot  be 
verified.  Thus  this  hypothesis  cannot  be  considered  as  anything 
more  than  a  speculation  or  conjecture  as  to  how  things  might 
have  happened. 


58  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

Now  it  would  be  equally  plausible  to  suggest  that  the  special 
form  of  marriage  is  the  result  of  the  terminology.  If,  as  in  the 
terminology  of  the  Omaha  type,  I  treat  my  wife's  brother's 
daughter  as  being  the  younger  sister  of  my  wife,  and,  by  the 
custom  of  the  sororate,  it  is  considered  proper  for  me  to  marry  my 
wife's  younger  sister,  then  I  might  well  be  permitted  to  marry  the 
woman  who,  in  the  terminological  system,  is  treated  as  such, 
namely  her  brother's  daughter.  This  hypothesis  is,  of  course, 
equally  lacking  in  proof.  If  we  adopt  the  Kohler  hypothesis  the 
terminology  is  conceived  to  be  in  some  sense  explained,  but  there 
is  no  explanation  of  the  marriage  custom.  By  the  alternative 
hypothesis  the  marriage  custom  is  explained,  but  the  terminology 
is  not.  I  do  not  see  how  there  can  be  any  ground  for  a  choice 
of  one  of  these  two  hypotheses  in  preference  to  the  other  except 
purely  personal  predilection. 

However,  while  we  could  conceive  of  the  marriage  custom 
as  being  the  immediate  result  of  the  terminology  in  a  society 
which  already  has  sororal  polygyny,  the  terminology  cannot  be 
the  immediate  result  of  the  marriage  custom  without  the  con- 
comitant action  of  some  other  undetermined  factor.  We  have  ex- 
amples of  societies  in  which  a  man  sometimes  marries  the  widow  of 
his  mother's  brother,  but  only  uses  the  terminology  which  this 
marriage  makes  appropriate  after  the  marriage  has  taken  place. 
Although  we  have  no  recorded  instance  of  this  procedure  in 
marriage  with  the  wife's  brother's  daughter  it  is  at  least  conceivable 
that  it  might  occur.  What  is  lacking  in  the  hypothesis  we  are 
examining  is  some  reason  why  the  whole  terminology  should  be 
adjusted  so  as  to  fit  a  particular  form  of  marriage  which  only 
occasionally  occurs. 

Let  us  now  leave  the  hypothesis  and  examine  the  structural 
principles  of  those  kinship  systems  in  which  this  terminology 
occurs,  whether  in  the  Choctaw  or  the  Omaha  form.  It  is  necessary, 
however,  to  say  something  on  the  subject  of  kinship  terminologies, 
about  which  there  has  been  a  great  deal  of  controversy.  Morgan's 
first  interest  in  the  subject  was  as  an  ethnologist,  i.e.  one  seeking 
to  discover  the  historical  relations  of  the  peoples  of  the  earth.  He 
thought  that  by  collecting  a  sufficient  sample  of  terminologies 
and  comparing  them  he  could  reveal  the  historical  relation  of  the 
American  Indians  (the  Ganowanian  peoples  as  he  called  them) 
to  the  peoples  of  Asia.  In  the  course  of  his  work,  however,  he 


THE   STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  59 

decided  that  these  terminologies  could  be  used  to  infer  the  former 
existence  of  forms  of  social  organisation.  He  supposed  that  the 
classificatory  terminology  which  he  found  in  North  American 
tribes  such  as  the  Iroquois  was  inconsistent  with  the  form  of 
social  organisation  with  which  it  is  actually  found,  and  therefore 
could  not  have  arisen  in  a  society  so  organised,  but  must  be  a 
'survival'  from  some  different  kind  of  social  system. 

This  was,  of  course,  pure  assumption,  but  it  is  the  kind  of 
assumption  that  the  method  of  conjectural  history  encourages 
us  to  make,  often  unconsciously  or  implicitly.  Morgan  was  thus 
led  to  a  hypothesis  that  is  one  of  the  most  fantastic  in  a  subject 
that  is  full  of  fantastic  hypotheses.  The  truth  is  that  he  had  quite 
failed  to  understand  the  nature  and  function  of  the  classificatory 
terminology.  There  is  nothing  that  so  effectively  prevents  the 
perception  and  understanding  of  things  as  they  are  as  hypotheses 
of  conjectural  history,  or  the  desire  to  invent  such  hypotheses. 

One  of  Morgan's  early  critics,  Starcke  (1889),  was,  I  believe, 
the  first  to  maintain  the  position  which  has  always  been  my  own. 
He  held  that  in  general  a  kinship  nomenclature  is  'the  faithful 
reflection  of  the  juridical  relations  which  arise  between  the  nearest  - 
kinsfolk  in  each  tribe'.  He  condemned  as  unsound  the  attempt 
to  use  such  nomenclatures  to  make  historical  reconstructions  of 
past  societies.  It  would  be  interesting  to  consider  why  it  is  that 
Starcke  has  had  so  few  followers  and  Morgan  so  many,  but  that 
I  cannot  here  undertake. 

In  1909  Kroeber  published  in  our  Journal  a  paper  on  'Classi- 
ficatory Systems  of  Relationship '.To  the  contentions  of  that  paper 
Rivers  made  a  reply  in  his  lectures  on  Kinship  and  Social  Or- 
ganisation (1914&),  and  Kroeber  answered  the  criticisms  of 
Rivers  in  his  California  Kinship  Systems  (1917). 

I  discussed  Kroeber's  paper  with  Rivers  when  it  appeared 
and  found  myself  in  the  position  of  disagreeing  with  both  sides 
of  the  controversy.  Kroeber  wrote:  'Nothing  is  more  precarious 
than  the  common  method  of  deducing  the  recent  existence  of 
social  or  marital  institutions  from  a  designation  of  relationship.' 
This  is  a  restatement  of  Starcke's  contention  of  1889,  and  with 
it  I  was,  and  still  am,  in  complete  agreement,  thereby  disagreeing 
with  Rivers.  Kroeber  also  wrote:  'It  has  been  an  unfortunate 
characteristic  of  the  anthropology  of  recent  years  to  seek  in  a 
great  measure    specific   causes   for   specific   events,   connection 


6o  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

between  which  can  be  established  only  through  evidence  that 
is  subjectively  selected.  On  wider  knowledge  and  freedom  from 
motive  it  is  becoming  increasingly  apparent  that  causal  explanations 
of  detached  anthropological  phenomena  can  be  but  rarely  found 
in  other  detached  phenomena.'  With  this  statement  I  am  in 
agreement. 

But  both  Kroeber  and  Rivers  seemed  to  agree  that  causal 
explanations  are  necessary  for  the  constitution  of  what  Kroeber 
calls  'true  science'.  For  Rivers  anthropology  is  a  true  science 
because,  or  to  the  extent  that,  it  can  show  causal  connections; 
for  Kroeber  it  is  not  a  true  science.  Here  I  disagree  with  both 
Kroeber  and  Rivers,  holding  that  a  pure  theoretical  science 
(whether  physical,  biological  or  social)  is  not  concerned  with 
causal  relations  in  this  sense.  The  concept  of  cause  and  effect 
belongs  properly  to  applied  science,  to  practical  life  and  its 
arts  and  techniques  and  to  history. 

This  brings  us  to  the  crux  of  the  Rivers-Kroeber  debate. 
Rivers  held  that  the  characteristics  of  a  kinship  nomenclature 
are  determined  by  social  or  sociological  factors,  that  particular 
features  of  terminology  result  from  particular  features  of  social 
organisation.  Against  this  Kroeber  held  that  the  features  of  a 
system  of  terminology  'are  determined  primarily  by  language' 
and  'reflect  psychology  not  sociology'.  'Terms  of  relationship', 
he  wrote,  'are  determined  primarily  by  linguistic  factors  and 
are  only  occasionally,  and  then  indirectly,  affected  by  social 
circumstances.'  But  in  his  later  paper  Kroeber  explains  that 
what  he  calls  psychological  factors  'are  social  or  cultural 
phenomena  as  thoroughly  and  completely  as  institutions,  beliefs 
or  industries  are  social  phenomena'.  His  thesis  is  therefore  con- 
cerned with  a  distinction  between  two  kinds  of  social  phenomena. 
One  of  these  he  calls  institutional,  defined  as  'practices  connected 
with  marriage,  descent,  personal  relations,  and  the  like'.  These 
are  what  he  called  in  his  first  paper  'social  factors'.  The  other 
kind  he  speaks  of  as  the  'psyche'  of  a  culture,  'that  is,  the  ways  of 
thinking  and  feeling  characteristic  of  the  culture'.  These  constitute 
what  he  calls  the  psychological  factors. 

Thus  Kroeber's  thesis,  on  its  positive  side,  is  that  similarities 
and  differences  of  kinship  nomenclature  are  to  be  interpreted  or 
understood  by  reference  to  similarities  and  differences  in  the 
general  'manner  of  thought'.  On  its  negative  side,  and  it  is  with 


THE  STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  6l 

this  that  we  are  concerned,  Kroeber's  thesis  is  that  there  is  no 
regular  close  connection  between  similarities  and  differences 
of  kinship  nomenclature  and  similarities  and  differences  of 
'institutions',  i.e.  practices  connected  with  marriage,  descent  and 
personal  relations.  He  admits,  in  19 17,  the  existence  of  'undoubted 
correspondence  of  terminology  and  social  practice  in  certain 
parts  of  Australia  and  Oceania',  but  denies  that  such  are  to  be 
found  in  California.  It  may  be  pointed  out  that  in  Australia  and 
Oceania  they  have  been  deliberately  looked  for,  in  California  they 
have  not.  It  may  well  be  that  in  the  remnants  of  Californian 
tribesJt  is  now  too  late  to  look  for  them. 

\ln_Qpposition  to  Kroeber,  and  in  a  certain  sense  in  agreement 
with  Rivers,  i  I  hold  that  all  over  the  world  there  are  impor- 
tant correspondences  between  kinship  nomenclature  and  social 
practices.  Such  correspondences  are  not  to  be  simply  assumed; 
they  must  be  demonstrated  by  field  ^^ork  and  comparative 
analysis^  But  their  absence  may  not  be  assumed  either;  and 
Kroeber's  arguments  from  their  alleged  absence  in  California 
remain,  I  think,  entirely  unconvincing.^ 

For  Kroeber  the  kinship  nomenclature  of  a  people  represents 
their  general  manner  of  thought  as  it  is  applied  to  kinship.  But 
the  institutions  of  a  people  also  represent  their  general  manner  of 
thought  about  kinship  and  marriage.  Are  we  to  suppose  that  in 
Californian  tribes  the  way  of  thinking  about  kinship  as  it  appears 
on  the  one  hand  in  the  terminology  and  on  the  other  hand  in 
social  customs  are  not  merely  different  but  are  not  connected? 
Tliis  seems  to  be  in  effect  what  Kroeber  is  proposing. 

Kroeber  pointed  out  in  19 17  that  his  original  paper  represented 
'a  genuine  attempt  to  understand  kinship  systems  as  kinship 
systems'.  But  by  'kinship  system'  Kroeber  means  only  a  system 
of  nomenclature.  Moreover,  Kroeber  is  an  ethnologist,  not  a 
social  anthropologist.  His  chief,  if  not  his  sole,  interest  in  the 
subject  is  in  the  possibility  of  discovering  and  defining  the 
historical  relations  of  peoples  by  comparison  of  their  systems  of 
nomenclature. 

My  own  conception  is  that  the  nomenclature  of  kinship  is 
an  intrinsic  part  of  a  kinship  system,  just  as  it  is  also,  of  course, 
an  intrinsic  part  of  a  language.  The  relations  between  the  nomen- 
clature and  the  rest  of  the  system  are  relations  within  an  ordered 
whole.  My  concern,  both  in  field  work  in  various  parts  of  the  world 


62  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

and  in  comparative  studies,  has  been  to  discover  the  nature  of 
these  relations. 

In  the  actual  study  of  a  kinship  system  the  nomenclature  is 
of  the  utmost  importance.  It  affords  the  best  possible  approach 
to  the  investigation  and  analysis  of  the  kinship  system  as  a  whole. 
This,  of  course,  it  could  not  do  if  there  were  no  real  relations  of 
interdependence  between  the  terminology  and  the  rest  of  the 
system.  That  there  are  such  relations  I  can  affirm  from  my  own 
field  work  in  more  than  one  region.  It  will  be  borne  out,  I  believe, 
by  any  anthropologist  who  has  made  a  thorough  field  study 
of  a  kinship  system.^ 

I  have  dealt  with  the  controversy  between  Kroeber  and 
Rivers  because,  as  both  the  controversialists  point  out,  the  real 
issue  is  not  simply  one  concerning  kinship  terms,  but  is  a  very 
important  question  of  the  general  method  of  anthropological 
studies.  It  seemed  to  me  that  I  could  best  make  clear  my  own 
position  by  showing  you  how  it  differs  from  that  of  Rivers  on 
the  one  side  and  that  of  Kroeber  on  the  other. 

Kinship  systems  are  made  and  re-made  by  man,  in  the  same 
sense  that  languages  are  made  and  re-made,  which  does  not  mean 
that  they  are  normally  constructed  or  changed  by  a  process  of 
deliberation  and  under  control  of  conscious  purpose.  A  language 
has  to  work,  i.e.  it  has  to  provide  a  more  or  less  adequate  in- 
strument for  communication,  and  in  order  that  it  may  work  it 
has  to  conform  to  certain  general  necessary  conditions.  A  morpho- 
logical comparison  of  languages  shows  us  the  different  ways  in 
which  these  conditions  have  been  complied  with  by  using  different 
morphological  principles  such  as  inflection,  agglutination,  word 
order,  internal  modification  or  the  use  of  tone  or  stress.  A  kinship 
system  also  has  to  work  if  it  is  to  exist  or  persist.  It  has  to  provide 
an  orderly  and  workable  system  of  social  relations  defined  by  social 
usage.  A  comparison  of  different  systems  shows  us  how  workable 
kinship  systems  have  been  created  by  utilising  certain  structural 
principles  and  certain  mechanisms.  .^ 

One  common  feature  of  kinship  systems  is  the  recognition 
of  certain  categories  or  kinds  into  which  the  various  relatives  of  a 

^  My  position  has  been  misunderstood  and  consequently  misrepresented 
by  Dr.  Opler  (1937ft)  in  his  paper  on  '  Apache  Data  concerning  the  Relation  of 
Kinship  Terminology  to  Social  Classification';  but  the  first  two  paragraphs 
of  another  of  Dr.  Opler's  papers  (1937a)  on  'Chiricahua  Apache  Social  Or- 
ganisation', state  what  was  at  that  time  his,  and  is  also  my,  point  of  view. 


^  THE  STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  63 

single  person  can  be  grouped.  The  actual  social  relation  between  a 
person  and  his  relative,  as  defined  by  rights  and  duties  or  socially 
approved  attitudes  and  modes  of  behaviour,  is  then  to  a  greater 
or  less  extent  fixed  by  the  category  to  which  the  relative  belongs. 
The  nomenclature  of  kinship  is  commonly  used  as  a  means  of 
establishing  and  recognising  these  categories,  A  single  term  may 
be  used  to  refer  to  a  category  of  relatives  and  different  categories 
will  be  distinguished  by  different  terms. 

Let  us  consider  a  simple  example  from  our  own  system. 
We  do  what  is  rather  unusual  in  the  general  nm  of  kinship 
systems:  we  regard  the  father's  brother  and  the  mother's  brother 
as  relatives  of  the  same  kind  of  category.  We  apply  a  single  term 
originally  denoting  the  mother's  brother  (from  the  Latin  avun- 
culus) to  both  of  them.  The  legal  relationship  in  English  law, 
except  for  entailed  estates  and  titles  of  nobility,  is  the  same  for  a 
nephew  and  either  of  his  uncles;  for  example,  the  nephew  has  the 
same  rights  of  inheritance  in  case  of  intestacy  over  the  estate  of 
either.  In  what  may  be  called  the  socially  standardised  behaviour 
of  England  it  is  not  possible  to  note  any  regular  distinction  made 
between  the  maternal  and  the  paternal  uncle.  Reciprocally  the 
relation  of  a  man  to  his  different  kinds  of  nephews  is  in  general  the 
same.  By  extension,  no  significant  difference  is  made  between 
the  son  of  one's  mother's  brother  and  the  son  of  one's  father's 
brother.  ^J^alJ?^^ 

In  Montenegro,  on  the  contrary,  to  take  another  European 
system,  the  father's  brothers  constitute  one  category  and  the 
mother's  brothers  another.  These  relatives  are  distinguished  by 
different  terms,  and  so  are  their  respective  wives,  and  the  social 
relations  in  which  a  man  stands  to  his  two  kinds  of  uncles  show 
marked  differences. 

There  is  nothing  'natural'  about  the  English  attitude  towards 
uncles.  Indeed  many  peoples  in  many  parts  of  the  world  would 
regard  this  failure  to  distinguish  between  relatives  on  the  father's 
side  and  those  on  the  mother's  side  as  unnatural  and  even  im- 
proper. But  the  terminology  is  consistent  with  our  whole  kinship 
system. 

The  kinship  systems  with  which  we  shall  be  concerned  here 
all  have  certain  forms  of  what  Morgan  called  the  'classificatory' 
terminology.  What  Morgan  meant  by  this  term  is  quite  clear  from 
his  writings,  but  his  definition  is  often  ignored,  perhaps  because 


64  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

people  do  not  bother  to  read  him.  A  nomenclaturejs-classiiicatory 
when  it  uses  terms  wliich  primariFy  appIy~toTineal  relatives,  such 
as  'father',  to  refer  also  to  collateral  relatives.  Thus  by  Morgan's 
definition  the  English  word  'uncle'  is  not  a  classificatory  term, 
but  the  very  opposite,  since  it  is  used  only  for  collateral  relatives. 
Kroeber  (1909)  criticises  Morgan  and  rejects  his  conception  of 
classificatory  terminologies,  and  then  proceeds  to  make  use  of  the 
same  distinction  by  taking  as  one  of  the  important  features  of 
terminologies  the  extent  to  which  they  separate  or  distinguish 
lineal  from  collateral  relatives.  It  seems  to  be  merely  the  word 
'classificatory'  that  Kroeber  does  not  like.  Doubtless  it  is  not  the 
ideal  word;  but  it  has  long  been  in  use  and  no  better  one  has  been 
suggested,  though  others  have  been  put  forward. 

I  do  not  propose  to  deal  with  all  systems  in  which  the  classi- 
ficatory principle  is  applied  in  the  terminology,  but  only  with  a 
certain  widespread  type.  In  these  systems  the  distinction  between 
lineal  and  collateral  relatives  is  clearly  recognised  and  is  of  great 
importance  in  social  life,  but  it  is  in  certain  respects  subordinated 
to  another  structural  principle,  which  can  be  spoken  of  as  the 
principle  of  the  solidarity  of  the  sibling  group.  A  group  of  siblings 
is  constituted  by  the  sons  and  daughters  of  a  man  and  his  wife  in 
monogamous  societies,  or  of  a  man  and  his  wives  where  there 
is  polygyny,  or  of  a  woman  and  her  husbands  in  polyandrous 
communities.  The  bond  uniting  brothers  and  sisters  together 
into  a  social  group  is  everywhere  regarded  as  important,  but  it  is 
more  emphasised  in  some  societies  than  in  others.  The  solidarity 
of  the  sibling  group  is  shown  in  the  first  instance  in  the  social 
relations  between  its  members. 

From  this  principle  there  is  derived  a  further  principle  which 
I  shall  speak  of  as  that  of  the  unity  of  the  sibling  group.  This 
refers  not  to  the  internal  unity  of  the  group  as  exhibited  in  the 
behaviour  of  members  to  one  another,  but  to  its  unity  in  relation 
to  a  person  outside  it  and  connected  with  it  by  a  specific  relation 
to  one  of  its  members. 

A  diagram  may  help  the  discussion.  Fig.  4  represents  a  sibling 
group  of  three  brothers  and  two  sisters,  to  which  Ego  is  related 
by  the  fact  that  he  is  the  son  of  one  of  the  three  men.  In  the 
kinship  systems  with  which  I  am  now  dealing.  Ego  regards  himself 
as  standing  in  the  same  general  kind  of  relation  to  all  the  members 
of  the  group.  For  him  it  constitutes  a  unity.  His  relation  to  the 


THE   STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  65 

brothers  and  sisters  of  his  father  is  conceived  as  being  of  the  same 
general  kind  as  his  relation  to  his  father.  Within  the  group, 
however,  there  are  two  principles  of  differentiation,  sex  and 
seniority,  which  have  to  be  taken  into  account.  In  systems  in  which 
seniority  is  not  emphasised  a  man  treats  his  father's  brothers, 
both  older  and  younger,  as  being  like  his  father.  He  refers  to 
them  or  addresses  them  by  the  same  term  of  kinship  that  he  applies 
to  his  own  father,  and  in  certain  important  respects  his  behaviour 
towards  them  is  similar  to  his  behaviour  towards  his  own  father. 
What  defines  this  behaviour  is,  of  course,  different  in  different 
systems.  Where  seniority  is  strongly  emphasised,  a  man  may 
distinguish  betv^een  the  senior  brother  and  the  junior  brother 
either  in  behaviour  alone  or  both  in  behaviour  and  terminology, 


A     0     A     0     A 

Ego 

Fig.  4 

but  there  still  remains  a  common  element  in  the  pattern  of  be- 
haviour towards  all  'fathers'. 

The  difference  of  sex  is  more  important  than  the  difference  of 
seniority,  and  in  this  matter  there  is  considerable  variation  in  the 
systems  we  are  considering.  But  in  quite  a  considerable  number 
of  systems,  in  different  parts  of  the  world,  there  are  certain  features 
of  a  man's  relationship  to  his  father's  sister  which  can  be  correctly 
described  by  saying  that  he  regards  her  as  a  sort  of  female  father. 
In  some  of  these  systems  he  actually  calls  her  'female  father', 
or  some  modification  of  the  term  for  father.  If  it  seems  to  you 
impossible  that  a  man  should  regard  his  father's  sister  as  a  relative 
of  the  same  kind  as  his  own  father,  this  is  because  you  are  thinking, 
not  about  social  relationships  as  defined  by  modes  of  behaviour, 
with  which  we  are  here  concerned,  but  about  the  physiological 
relationship,  which  is  irrelevant. 

The  same  kind  of  thing  happens  with  the  sibling  group  of  the 
mother.  The  mother's  sisters  are  treated  as  relatives  of  the  same 
kind  as  the  mother,  both  in  terminology  and  in  certain  principles 
of  behaviour  or  attitude.  In  a  number  of  systems  the  mother's 
brother  is  also  treated  as  a  relative  of  the  same  kind  as  the  mother. 
3 


66  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

He  may  be  called  'male  mother',  as  in  Bantu  tribes  of  Africa  and  in 
Tonga  in  the  Pacific.  If  the  principle  of  seniority  is  stressed,  the 
mother's  brothers  may  be  distinguished  according  as  they  are 
older  or  younger  than  the  mother. 

Those  of  you  who  have  never  had  any  direct  contact  with 
systems  of  this  kind  may  find  it  difficult  to  comprehend  how  a 
father's  sister  can  be  regarded  as  a  female  father  or  a  mother's 
brother  as  a  male  mother.  This  is  due  to  the  difficulty  of  dissociating 
the  terms  'father'  and  'mother'  from  the  connotations  they  have  in 
our  own  social  system.  It  is  absolutely  essential  to  do  this  if  the 
kinship  systems  of  other  societies  are  ever  to  be  understood. 
Perhaps  it  will  help  somewhat  if  I  refer  to  another  terminology 
which  seems  to  us  peculiar.  Most  of  the  systems  with  which  I  am 
now  dealing  have  a  word  for  'child',  or  words  for  'son'  and 
'daughter',  which  a  man  applies  to  his  own  children  and  his 
brother's  children,  and  a  woman  applies  to  her  own  children  and 
her  sister's  children.  But  in  some  Australian  tribes  there  are  two 
different  words  for  'child'.  One  is  used  by  a  man  for  his  own  child 
(or  his  brother's  child)  and  by  a  woman  for  her  brother's  child; 
the  other  is  used  by  a  woman  for  her  own  or  her  sister's  child,  and 
by  a  man  for  his  sister's  child.  I  think  you  will  see  that  this  is 
another  way  of  expressing  in  the  terminology  the  unity  that  links 
brother  and  sister  in  relation  to  the  child  of  either  of  them.  I  am 
called  by  one  term  by  my  father  and  his  brothers  and  sisters; 
and  by  another  term  by  my  mother  and  her  sisters  and  brothers. 

The  same  principle,  that  of  the  unity  of  the  sibling  group, 
is  applied  to  other  sibling  groups.  Thus  the  father's  father's 
brother  is  regarded  as  belonging  to  the  same  category  as  the 
father's  father,  with  the  result  that  his  son  is  a  somewhat  more 
distant  relative  of  the  same  kind  as  the  father  and  his  brothers. 
By  means  of  such  extension  of  the  basic  principle,  a  very  large 
number  of  collateral  relatives  of  different  degrees  of  distance  can 
be  brought  under  a  limited  number  of  categories.  A  man  may 
have  many,  even  hundreds,  of  relatives  whom  he  thus  classifies 
as  'fathers',  'brothers',  'mother's  brothers'  and  so  on.  But  there  are 
different  ways  in  which  this  extension  of  the  basic  classificatory 
principle  can  be  applied,  so  that  there  result  systems  of  different 
types.  What  is  conmion  to  them  all  is  that  they  make  some  use 
of  this  structural  principle  which  I  have  briefly  illustrated. 

What   I  am  trying  to  show-you  is  that  the  classificatory 


THE  STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  67 

terminology_iA_Ji_jnethod  of  providing  a  wide-riange  Jciii^ipL^ 
organisation,  by  making  use  of  the  unity  of  the  sibling  group 
in  order  to  establish  a  few  categories  of  relationship  under  which 
a  very  large  number  of  near  and  distant  relatives  can  be  included.. 
For  all  the  relatives  who  are  denoted  by  one  term,  there  is  normally  ( 
some  element  of  attitude  or  behaviour  that  is  regarded  as  ap-  ' 
propriate  to  them  and  not  to  others.  But  within  a  category  there 
may  be  and  always  are  important  distinctions.  There  is,  first, 
the  very  important  distinction  between  one's  own  father  and 
his  brother.  There  are  distinctions  within  the  category  between 
nearer  and  more  distant  relatives.  There  is  sometimes  an  im- 
portant distinction  between  relatives  of  a  certain  category  who 
belong  to  other  clans.  There  are  other  distinctions  that  are  made 
in  different  particular  systems.  Thus  the  categories  represented 
by  the  terminology  never  give  us  anything  more  than  the  skeleton 
of  the  real  ordering  of  relatives  in  the  social  life.  But  in  every 
system  that  I  have  been  able  to  study  they  do  give  us  this  skeleton. 

If  this  thesis  is  true,  if  this  is  what  the  classificatory  ter- 
minology actually  is  in  the  tribes  in  which  it  exists,  it  is  obvious 
that  Morgan's  whole  theor\'  is  entirely  ungrounded.  The  classi- 
ficatory system,  as  thus  interpreted,  depends  upon  the  recognition 
of  the  strong  social  ties  that  unite  brothers  and  sisters  of  the  same 
elementary  family,  and  the  utilisation  of  this  tie  to  build  up  a 
complex  orderly  arrangement  of  social  relations  amongst  kin. 
It  could  not  come  into  existence  except  in  a  society  based  on 
the  elementary  family.  Nowhere  in  the  world  are  the  ties  between 
a  man  and  his  own  children  or  between  children  of  one  father 
stronger  than  in  Australian  tribes,  which,  as  you  know,  present 
an  extreme  example  of  the  classificatory  terminology. 

The  internal  solidarity  of  the  sibling  group,  and  its  unity 
in  relation  to  persons  connected  with  it,  appear  in  a  great  number 
of  different  forms  in  different  societies.  I  cannot  make  any  attempt 
to  deal  with  these,  but  for  the  sake  of  the  later  arginnent  I  will 
point  out  that  it  is  in  the  light  of  this  structural  principle  that  we 
must  interpret  the  customs  of  sororal  polygyny  (marriage  with 
two  or  more  sisters),  the  sororate  (marriage  with  the  deceased 
wife's  sister),  adelphic  polyandry  (marriage  of  a  woman  with  two 
or  more  brothers,  by  far  the  commonest  form  of  polyandry),  and 
the  levirate  (marriage  with  the  brother's  widow).  Sapir,  using  the 
method  of  conjectural  history,  has  suggested  that  the  classificatory 


68  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

terminology  may  be  the  result  of  the  customs  of  the  levirate  and 
sororate.  That  the  two  things  are  connected  is,  I  think,  clear, 
but  for  the  supposed  causal  connection  there  is  no  evidence  w^hat- 
ever.  Their  real  connection  is  that  they  are  different  ways  of 
applying  or  using  the  principle  of  the  unity  of  the  sibling  group, 
and  they  may  therefore  exist  together  or  separately. 

An  organisation  into  clans  or  moieties  is  also  based  on  the 
principle  of  the  solidarity  and  unity  of  the  sibling  group  in  com- 
bination with  other  principles.  Tylor  suggested  a  connection 
between  exogamous  clans  and  the  classificatory  terminology. 
Rivers  put  this  in  terms  of  conjectural  history,  and  argued  that  the 
classificatory  terminology  must  have  had  its  origin  in  the  or- 
ganisation of  society  into  exogamous  moieties. 

II 

It  is  necessary,  for  our  analysis,  to  consider  briefly  another 
aspect  of  the  structure  of  kinship  systems,  namely  the  division 
into  generations.  The  distinction  of  generation  has  its  basis  in  the 
elementary  family,  in  the  relation  of  parents  and  children.  A 
certain  generalising  tendency  is  discoverable  in  many  kinship 
systems  in  the  behaviour  of  relatives  of  different  generations. 
Thus  we  find  very  frequently  that  a  person  is  expected  to  adopt 
an  attitude  of  more  or  less  marked  respect  towards  all  his  relatives 
of  the  first  ascending  generation.  There  are  restraints  on  behaviour 
which  maintain  a  certain  distance  or  prevent  too  close  an  in- 
timacy. There  is,  in  fact,  a  generalised  relation  of  ascendancy 
and  subordination  between  the  two  generations.  This  is  usually 
accompanied  by  a  relation  of  friendly  equality  between  a  person 
and  his  relatives  of  the  second  ascending  generation.  The  nomen- 
clature for  grandparents  and  grandchildren  is  of  significance  in 
this  connection.  In  some  classificatory  systems,  such  as  those  of 
Australian  tribes,  the  grandparents  on  the  father's  side  are  dis- 
tinguished, in  terminology  and  in  behaviour,  from  those  on  the 
mother's  side.  But  in  many  classificatory  systems  the  generalising 
tendency  results  in  all  relatives  of  the  generation  being  classed 
together  as  'grandfathers'  and  'grandmothers'. 

We  may  note  in  passing  that  in  classificatory  terminologies 
of  what  Morgan  called  the  Malayan  type  and  Rivers  the  Hawaiian 
type,  this  generalising  process  is  applied  to  other  generations, 


THE   STUDY   OF   KINSHIP  SYSTEMS  69 

SO  that  all  relatives  of  the  parents'  generation  may  be  called 
'father'  and  'mother'  and  all  those  of  one's  own  generation  may 
be  called  'brother'  and  'sister'. 

There  are  many  kinship  systems  in  various  parts  of  the  world 
that  exhibit  a  structural  principle  which  I  shall  speak  of  as  the 
combination  of  alternate  generations.  This  means  that  relatives  of 
the  grandfather's  generation  are  thought  of  as  combined  with  those 
of  one's  own  generation  over  against  the  relatives  of  the  parents' 
generation.  The  extreme  development  of  this  principle  is  to  be 
seen  in  Australian  tribes.  I  shall  refer  to  this  later. 

While  some  systems  emphasise  the  distinction  of  generations 
in  their  terminology  or  in  their  social  structure,  there  are  also 
systems  in  which  relatives  of  two  or  more  generations  are  in- 
cluded in  a  single  category.  So  far  as  I  have  been  able  to  make  a 
comparative  study,  the  various  instances  of  this  seem  to  fall  into 
four  classes. 

In  one  class  of  instances  the  term  of  relationship  does  not 
carry  a  connotation  referring  to  any  particular  generation  and  is 
used  to  mark  off  a  sort  of  marginal  region  between  non-relatives 
and  those  close  relatives  towards  whom  specific  duties  and  over 
whom  specific  rights  are  recognised.  The  application  of  the  term 
generally  only  implies  that  since  the  other  person  is  recognised  as  a 
relative  he  or  she  must  be  treated  with  a  certain  general  attitude 
of  friendliness  and  not  as  a  stranger.  A  good  example  is  provided 
by  the  terms  ol-le-sotwa  and  en-e-sotwa  in  Masai.  I  would  include 
the  English  word  'cousin'  in  this  class. 

A  second  class  of  instances  includes  those  in  which  there  is 
conflict  or  inconsistency  between  the  required  attitude  towards  a 
particular  relative  and  the  required  general  attitude  towards  the 
generation  to  which  he  belongs.  Thus  in  some  tribes  in  South- 
East  Africa  there  is  conflict  between  the  general  rule  that  relatives 
of  the  first  ascending  generation  are  to  be  treated  with  marked 
respect  and  the  custom  of  privileged  disrespect  towards  the 
mother's  brother.  This  is  resolved  by  placing  the  mother's 
brother  in  the  second  ascending  generation  and  calling  him 
'grandfather'.  An  opposite  example  is  found  in  the  Masai.  A 
man  is  on  terms  of  familiarity  with  all  his  relatives  of  the  second 
descending  generation,  who  are  his  'grandchildren'.  But  it  is  felt 
that  the  relation  between  a  man  and  the  wife  of  his  son's  son 
should  be  one  not  of  familiarity  but  of  marked  reserve.  The 


70  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN  PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

inconsistency  is  resolved  by  a  sort  of  legal  fiction  by  which  she  is 
moved  out  of  her  generation  and  is  called  'son's  wife'. 

A  third  class  of  instances  are  those  resulting  from  the  struc- 
tural principle,  already  mentioned,  whereby  alternate  generations 
are  combined.  Thus  the  father's  father  may  be  called  'older  brother' 
and  treated  as  such,  and  the  son's  son  may  be  called  'younger 
brother'.  Or  a  man  and  his  son's  son  may  be  both  included  in  a 
single  category  of  relationship.  There  are  many  illustrations 
of  this  in  Australian  tribes  and  some  elsewhere.  An  example 
from  the  Hopi  will  be  given  later. 

The  fourth  class  of  instances  includes  the  systems  of  Choctaw 
and  Omaha  type  and  also  certain  others,  and  in  these  the  dis- 
tinction betsveen  generations  is  set  aside  in  favour  of  another 
principle,  that  of  the  unity  of  the  lineage  group. 

Since  the  word  lineage  is  often  loosely  used,  I  must  explain 
what  I  mean  by  it.  A  patrilineal  or  agnatic  hneage  consists  of  a 
man  and  all  his  descendants  through  males  for  a  determinate 
number  of  generations.  Thus  a  minimal  lineage  includes  three 
generations,  and  we  can  have  lineages  of  four,  five  or  n  generations. 
A  matrilineal  lineage  consists  of  a  woman  and  all  her  descendants 
through  females  for  a  determinate  number  of  generations.  A 
lineage  group  consists  of  all  the  members  of  a  lineage  who  are  alive 
at  a  particular  time.  A  clan,  as  I  shall  use  the  term  here,  is  a 
group  which,  though  not  actually  or  demonstrably  (by  genealogies) 
a  lineage,  is  regarded  as  being  in  some  ways  similar  to  a  lineage. 
It  normally  consists  of  a  number  of  actual  lineages.  Lineages, 
both  patrilineal  and  matrilineal,  exist  implicitly  in  any  kinship 
system,  but  it  is  only  in  some  systems  that  the  solidarity  of  the 
lineage  group  is  an  important  feature  in  the  social  structure. 

Where  lineage  groups  are  important  we  can  speak  of  the 
solidarity  of  the  group,  which  shows  itself  in  the  first  instance 
in  the  internal  relations  between  the  members.  By  the  principle 
of  the  unity  of  the  lineage  group  I  mean  that  for  a  person  who 
does  not  belong  to  the  lineage  but  is  connected  with  it  through 
some  important  bond  of  kinship  or  by  marriage,  its  members 
constitute  a  single  category,  with  a  distinction  within  the  category 
between  males  and  females,  and  possibly  other  distinctions  also. 
When  this  principle  is  applied  in  the  terminology  a  person 
connected  with  a  lineage  from  outside  applies  to  its  members,  of 
one  sex,  through  at  least  three  generations,  the  same  term  of 


THE  STUDY  OF  KINSHIP  SYSTEMS  7I 

relationship.  In  its  extreme  development,  as  applied  to  the  clan,  a 
person  connected  with  a  clan  in  a  certain  way  applies  a  single 
term  of  relationship  to  all  members  of  the  clan.  An  example  will 
be  given  later. 

The  Omaha  type  of  terminology  may  be  illustrated  by  the 
system  of  the  Fox  Indians,  which  has  been  carefully  studied  by 
Dr.  Sol  Tax  (1937).  The  features  of  the  system  that  are  relevant 


1 

A  = 
GF 

=  0 
gm  ' 

0    = 

A 
BL 

A 
BL 

A 
BL 

.^ 

•t 

A  = 
F 

=  0 
tn 

1 
0   = 

fs     [ 

1 
A 

N 

I 

0 
n 

1 

A  = 
B 

=   0 

1 

A 
EGO 

1 

0   = 

sis    [ 

1 

A 
N 

0 
n 

1 

A 
S 

0 
d 

Fig.  s— Fox 

Father's  Lineage 

1 
A 

N 

1 

0 

n 

to  the  argument  are  illustrated  in  the  accompanying  diagrams 
(Figs.  5-9).i 

In  his  own  patrilineal  lineage  a  man  distinguishes  his  relatives 
according  to  generation  as  'grandfather'  (GF),  'father'  (F), 
'older  or  younger  brother'  (B),  'son'  (S),  'grandmother'  (gm), 

^  In  these  diagrams  A  represents  a  male  person  and  O  a  female.  The  sign 
=  connects  a  man  and  his  wife  and  the  lines  descending  from  it  indicate  their 
children.  The  letters  (capitals  for  males  and  lower  case  for  females)  stand  for  the 
kinship  terms  of  a  classificatory  system,  in  which  the  same  term  is  applied  to  a 
number  of  relatives.  GF  stands  for  the  term  used  in  referring  to  a  grandfather, 
and  similarly  gm  for  grandmother;  the  others  are  F,  father,  m,  mother,  ms, 
mother's  sister,  fs,  father's  sister,  MB,  mother's  brother,  FL,  father-in-law, 
ml,  mother-in-law,  B,  brother,  sis,  sister,  BL,  brother-in-law,  si,  sister-in-law, 
S,  son,  d,  daughter,  N,  nephew  (strictly  speaking  sister's  son)  n,  niece  (sister's 
daughter  of  a  male)  GC  or  gc,  grandchild. 


72  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

'father's  sister'  (fs),  'sister'  (sis),  and  'daughter'  (d).  I  would  draw 
your  attention  to  the  fact  that  he  appHes  a  single  term,  'brother-in- 
law'  (BL),  irrespective  of  generation,  to  the  husbands  of  the  women 
of  the  lineage  through  three  generations  (his  own  and  the  two 
ascending  generations),  and  that  he  calls  the  children  of  all  these 
women  by  the  same  terms,  'nephew'  (N)  and  'niece'  (n).  Thus  the 
women  of  Ego's  own  lineage  of  these  generations  constitute  a  sort 
of  group,  and  Ego  regards  himself  as  standing  in  the  same  relation- 
ship to  the  children  and  husbands  of  all  of  them,  although  these 
persons  belong  to  a  number  of  different  lineages. 


1 

A  = 
GF 

=  O 
gm 

o  = 

gm  1^ 

A 
F 

A 
F 

A 
F 

A 
F 

1 

A  = 
MB 

=  O 

fs 

1 

0 
ms 

1 
O  = 

1 

A 
B 

1 

P 
sis 

1 

A  = 
MB 

=  O 

fs 

I 

O  = 
ms   1 

1 

A 

B 

EC 

1 

O 
sis 

JO 

1 
A  = 
MB 

=  O 
fs 

Fig.  6- 

M  other's 

1 

O  = 
ms 

-Fox 

Lineage 

1 

A 

B 

1 

O 
sis 

Turning  to  the  mother's  patrilineal  lineage,  it  can  be  seen 
that  a  man  calls  his  mother's  father  'grandfather',  but  calls  all  the 
males  of  the  lineage  in  the  three  succeeding  generations  'mother's 
brother'  (MB).  Similarly  he  calls  the  women  of  these  three 
generations,  except  his  own  mother,  by  a  term  translated  as 
'mother's  sister'  (ms).  He  applies  the  term  'father'  (F)  to  the 
husbands  of  all  the  women  of  the  lineage  through  four  generations 
(including  the  husband  of  the  mother's  father's  sister)  and  the 
children  of  all  these  women  are  his  'brothers'  and  'sisters'. 
He  is  the  son  of  one  particular  woman  of  a    unified   group, 


THE  STUDY  OF  KINSHIP  SYSTEMS  73 

and  the  sons  of  the  other  women  of  the  group  are  therefore  his 
'brothers'. 


A  = 
GF 


A  = 
GF 


A 
GF 


O  = 
gm 


O 
gm 

Fig.  7 — Fox 

Father's  Mother's  Lineage 


EGO 


A  =  O 
FL       ml 


A  = 
BL 


A  = 
BL 


A 
BL 


O 
si 

Fig.  8— Fox 

Wife's  Lineage 


O  =  A 
Wife  EGO 


In  his  father's  mother's  hneage  Ego  calls  all  the  men  and 
women  throughout  three  generations  'grandfather'  and  'grand- 
mother'. The  children  of  these  'grandmothers'  are  all  his  'fathers' 
and  'father's  sisters',  irrespective  of  generation.  In  his  mother's 


74 


STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN  PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 


mother's  lineage  he  also  calls  all  the  males  'grandfather'  and  the 
females  'grandmother',  but  I  have  not  thought  it  necessary  to 
include  a  figure  to  show  this. 

In  his  wife's  lineage  a  man  calls  his  wife's  father  by  a  term 
which  we  will  translate  'father-in-law'  (FL).  It  is  a  modification 
of  the  word  for  'grandfather'.^  The  sons  and  brother's  sons  of 
the  'fathers-in-law'  are  'brothers-in-law'  (BL),  and  the  daughters 
are  'sisters-in-law'  (si).  The  children  of  a  'brother-in-law*  are 
again  'brother-in-law'  and  'sister-in-law'.  Thus  these  two  terms 
are  applied  to  the  men  and  women  of  a  lineage  through  three 


A 
FL 


O  -  A 
ml    I    FL 


A  = 
FL 


A 
FL 


O  =  A 
Wife  EGO 


Fig.  9 — Fox 
Wife's  Mother's  Lineage 


generations.  The  children  of  all  these  'sisters-in-law'  are  'sons' 
and  'daughters'. 

Fig.  9  shows  the  lineage  of  the  wife's  mother.  In  this  lineage, 
through  three  generations,  all  the  men  are  called  'father-in-law' 
and  all  the  women  'mother-in-law'. 

Is  the  classification  of  relatives  in  the  Fox  terminology 
simply  a  matter  of  language,  as  some  would  have  us  believe? 
Dr.  Tax's  observations  (1937)  enable  us  to  affirm  that  it  is  not. 
He  writes: 

The  kinship  terminology  is  applied  to  all  known  relatives  (even  in 
some  cases  where  the  genealogical  relationship  is  not  traceable)  so  that 
the  entire  tribe  is  divided  into  a  small  number  of  types  of  relationship 

^  The  Fox  terms  for  father-in-law  and  mother-in-law  are  modifications 
of  the  terms  for  grandfather  and  grandmother.  In  the  Omaha  tribe  the  terms 
for  grandparents,  without  modification,  are  applied  to  the  parents-in-law  and 
to  those  who  are  called  'father-in-law'  and  'mother-in-law'  in  the  Fox  tribe. 


THE   STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  75 

pairs.  Each  of  these  types  carries  with  it  a  more  or  less  distinct  tradi- 
tional pattern  of  behaviour.  Generally  speaking,  the  behaviour  of  close 
relatives  follows  the  pattern  in  its  greatest  intensity,  that  of  farther 
relatives  in  lesser  degree  ;  but  there  are  numerous  cases  where,  for 
some  reason,  a  pair  of  close  relatives  '  do  not  behave  towards  each  other 
at  all  as  they  should'. 

Dr.  Tax  goes  on  to  define  the  patterns  of  behaviour  for  the 
various  types  of  relationship.  Thus  the  classification  of  relatives 
into  categories,  carried  out  by  means  of  the  nomenclature,  or 
therein  expressed,  appears  also  in  the  regulation  of  social 
behaviour.  There  is  good  evidence  that  this  is  true  of  other 
systems  of  Omaha  type,  and,  contrary  to  Kroeber's  thesis,  we  may 
justifiably  accept  the  hypothesis  that  it  is  probably  true  of  all. 

Charts  similar  to  those  given  here  for  the  Fox  Indians  can 
be  made  for  other  systems  of  the  Omaha  type.  I  think  that  a 
careful  examination  and  comparison  of  the  various  systems  shows 
that,  while  there  are  variations,  there  is  a  single  structural  principle 
underlying  both  the  terminology  and  the  associated  social  structure. 
A  lineage  of  three  (or  sometimes  more)  generations  is  regarded  as  a 
unity.  A  person  is  related  to  certain  lineages  at  particular  points: 
in  the  Fox  tribe  to  the  lineages  of  his  mother,  his  father's  mother, 
his  mother's  mother,  his  wife,  and  his  wife's  mother.  In  each 
instance  he  regards  himself  as  related  to  the  succeeding  generations 
of  the  lineage  in  the  same  way  as  he  is  related  to  the  generation 
with  which  he  is  actually  connected.  Thus  all  the  men  of  his 
mother's  lineage  are  his  'mother's  brothers',  those  of  his  'grand- 
mother's lineage  his  'grandfathers',  and  those  of  his  wife's  lineage 
are  his  'brothers-in-law'. 

This  structural  principle  of  the  unity  of  the  patrilineal 
lineage  is  not  a  hypothetical  cause  of  the  terminology.  It  is  a 
principle  that  is  directly  discoverable  by  comparative  analysis 
of  systems  of  this  type;  or,  in  other  words,  it  is  an  immediate 
abstraction  from  observed  facts. 

Let  us  now  examine  a  society  in  which  the  principle  of  the 
unity  of  the  lineage  group  is  applied  to  matrilineal  lineages. 
For  this  I  select  the  system  of  the  Hopi  Indians,  which  has  been 
analysed  in  a  masterly  manner  by  Dr.  Fred  Eggan  (1933)  in  a 
Ph.D.  thesis  which  has,  unfortunately,  not  yet  been  published.^ 

^  The  thesis,  in  a  revised  form,  has  now  been  published.  Eggan:  Social 
Organisation  of  the  Western  Pueblos.  The  University  of  Chicago  Press,  1950. 


76  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

The  most  significant  features  of  the  system  are  illustrated  in  the 
accompanying  figures. 


A  = 
GF 

1 
=  0 
gm 

1 

A  =  0 

B    i    si 

^ 

A  ' 
F 

1 

=  0 

m 

1 

A  = 
MB   [si 

1      ^ 

child 

A  = 
BL 

1 

=  0 

sis 

I 

A 
EGO 

1 
A  =  0 
B    1    si 

1              1 

A          0 

child 

A  = 
BL 

=   0 

n 

I 
A  =  0 

N  L 

1        ci 

child 

A  = 
BL 

=  0 

Fig.  10- 
Mother's 

1 

A 
B 

-Hopi 
Lineage 

1                   1 

A          0 
chiki 

A  man's  own  lineage  is,  of  course,  that  of  his  mother.  He 
distinguishes  the  women  of  his  lineage  by  generation  as  'grand- 
mother' (gm),  'mother'  (m),  'sister'  (sis),  'niece'  (n),  and  'grand- 
child' (gc).  Amongst  the  men  of  his  lineage  he  distinguishes  his 
'mother's  brothers'  (MB),  'brothers'  (B)  and  'nephews'  (N). 
But  he  includes  his  mother's  mother's  brother  and  his  sister's 
daughter's  son  in  the  same  category  as  his  brothers.  The  structural 
principle  exhibited  here  is  that  already  referred  to  as  the  com- 
bination of  alternate  generations.  It  should  be  noted  that  a  man 
includes  the  children  of  all  men  of  his  own  lineage,  irrespective 
of  generation,  in  the  same  category  as  his  own  children.  Fig.  10 
should  be  carefully  compared  with  Fig.  5,  for  the  Fox  Indians,  as 
the  comparison  is  illuminating. 


THE   STUDY   OF    KINSHIP   SYSTEMS 


77 


In  his  father's  Uneage  a  man  calls  all  the  male  members 
through  five  generations  'father'  and,  with  the  exception  of  his 
father's  mother  (his  'grandmother'),  he  calls  all  the  women 
'father's  sister'.  The  husband  of  any  woman  of  the  lineage  is  a 
'grandfather',  and  the  wife  of  any  man  of  the  lineage  is  a  'mother'. 


A   =  O 
GF      gm 


A  =  O 
GF        fa 


A  =  O 
GF       fs 


A 
GF 


A   =  O 
GF      fs 


Fig.  II  — Hopi 
Father's  Lineage 


The  children  of  his  'fathers'  are  'brothers'  and  'sisters'.  Fig.  ii 
should  be  carefully  compared  with  Fig.  6. 

In  his  mother's  father's  lineage  a  man  calls  all  the  men 
and  women  through  four  generations  'grandfather'  and  'grand- 
mother'. 

The  Hopi  do  not  regard  a  man  as  related  to  his  father's  father's 
lineage  as  a  whole,  and  the  principle  is  therefore  not  applied  to  it. 
He  does  call  his  own  father's  father  'grandfather'. 

Dr.  Eggan  has  shown  that  for  the  Hopi  this  classification 
of  relatives  into  categories  is  not  simply  a  matter  of  terminology 


78  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

or  language,  but   is  the   basis  of  much   of  the   regulation  of 
social  life. 

What  is,  I  think,  clearly  brought  out  by  a  comparison  of  the 
Fox  and  Hopi  systems  is  their  fundamental  similarity.  By  the 
theories  of  conjectural  history  this  similarity  is  the  accidental 
result  of  different  historical  processes.  By  my  theory  it  is  the 
result  of  the  systematic  application  of  the  same  structural  principle, 
in  one  instance  to  patrilineal  and  in  the  other  to  matrilineal  lineages. 


A  = 
GF 

1 
=  0 
gm 

A   =  0 
GF  Igm 

^ 

A   = 
GF 

1 
=   0 
gm 

A  -  0 
GF      gm 

! 

A      = 
MB 

EC 

=   C 
n 

A   = 
GF 

1 
=  0 
gm 

1 

A  =  0 
GF       gm 

JO 

A   = 
GF 

=   0 
gm 

Fig 
Mother's 

1 

A   =  0 
GF       gm 

12 — Hopi 
Father's  Lineage 

I  cannot,  of  course,  discuss  all  the  various  systems  of  Choctaw 
and  Omaha  type.  The  variations  that  they  show  in  certain  features 
are  very  interesting  and  important.  If  you  wish  to  test  my  theory 
you  will  examine  them,  or  some  of  them,  for  yourselves,  and  the 
easiest  way  to  analyse  any  system  is  to  reduce  it  to  a  set  of  lineage 
charts  similar  to  those  given  here  for  the  Fox  and  the  Hopi. 
For  any  system  such  a  set  of  charts  will  reveal  the  exact  way  in 
which  the  general  principle  of  the  unity  of  the  lineage  is  applied. 
The  manner  of  application  varies  somewhat,  but  the  principle 
appears  in  each  system  of  the  type. 

You  will  doubtless  already  have  noticed  that  in  these  systems 
there  are  an  extraordinary  number  of  relatives  of  all  ages  to  whom 


THE  STUDY   OF   KINSHIP  SYSTEMS  79 

a  man  applies  the  terms  'grandfather'  and  'grandmother'.  There 
is,  I  beheve,  a  good  reason  for  this,  which  should  be  briefly 
indicated.  It  is  a  general  rule  in  societies  having  a  classificatory 
terminology  that  for  all  the  various  relatives  included  under  a 
single  term  there  is  some  more  or  less  definite  pattern  of  behaviour 
which  is  regarded  as  normal  or  appropriate.  But  there  are  important 
differences  in  this  matter.  In  certain  instances  the  pattern  can 
be  defined  by  reference  to  specific  rights  and  duties,  or  by  specific 
modes  of  behaviour.  For  example,  in  the  Kariera  tribe  of  Australia 
a  man  must  practice  the  most  careful  avoidance  of  all  women  who 
are  included  in  the  category  of  'father's  sister',  of  whom  there  are 
very  many  and  of  whom  his  wife's  mother  is  one.  But  in  other 
instances  all  that  the  application  of  a  term  implies  is  a  certain 
general  attitude  rather  than  any  more  specific  relation.  Within 
such  a  category  there  may  be  a  specific  jural  or  personal  relation 
to  a  particular  individual.  In  many  classificatory  systems  the  terms 
for  grandfather  and  grandmother  are  used  in  this  way,  as  implying 
a  general  attitude  of  friendliness,  relatively  free  from  restraint, 
towards  all  persons  to  whom  they  are  applied.  Grandparents  and 
grandchildren  are  persons  with  whom  one  can  be  on  free  and 
easy  terms.  This  is  connected  with  an  extremely  widespread, 
indeed  almost  universal,  way  of  organising  the  relation  of  alternate 
generations  to  one  another. 

In  the  Fox  and  Hopi  systems  all  the  members  of  the  lineage 
of  a  grandparent  are  included  in  one  category  with  the  grand- 
parents and  the  attitude  that  is  appropriate  towards  a  grandparent 
is  extended  to  them.  This  does  not  imply  any  definite  set  of  rights 
and  duties,  but  only  a  certain  general  type  of  behaviour,  of  a  kind 
that  is  regarded  as  appropriate  towards  relatives  of  the  second 
ascending  generation  in  a  great  many  societies  not  belonging  to  the 
Choctaw  and  Omaha  type. 

I  should  have  liked  to  discuss  this  further  and  to  have  dealt 
with  those  varieties  of  the  Omaha  type  (such  as  the  VaNdau) 
in  which  the  mother's  brother  and  the  mother's  brother's  son  are 
called  'grandfather'.  But  I  have  only  time  to  draw  your  attention 
to  a  special  variety  of  the  Choctaw  type  which  is  of  great  interest 
in  this  connection.  The  Cherokee  were  divided  into  seven 
matrilineal  clans.  In  the  father's  clan  a  man  called  all  the  men  and 
women  of  his  father's  and  all  succeeding  generations  'father'  and 
'father's  sister',  and  this  clan  and  all  its  individual  members 


8o  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

had  to  be  treated  with  great  respect.  A  man  could  not  marry  a 
woman  of  his  father's  clan,  and  of  course  he  could  not  marry  into 
his  own  clan.  In  the  clan  of  his  father's  father  and  that  of  his 
mother's  father  a  man  calls  all  the  women  of  all  generations 
'grandmother'.  He  thus  treats,  not  the  lineage,  but  the  w'hole 
clan  as  a  unity,  although  a  clan  must  have  numbered  many 
hundreds  of  persons.  With  any  woman  whom  he  calls  'grand- 
mother' a  man  is  allowed  to  be  on  free  and  easy  terms.  It  was 
regarded  as  particullary  appropriate  that  a  man  should  marry  a 
'grandmother',  i.e.  a  woman  of  his  mother's  father's  or  father's 
father's  clan. 

Let  us  now  return  to  a  brief  consideration  of  the  special 
customs  of  marriage  that  have  been  proposed  as  causes  of  the 
Choctaw  and  Omaha  terminologies  respectively.  Marriage  w4th 
the  wife's  brother's  daughter  is  theoretically  possible  and  does 
perhaps  actually,  though  only  occasionally,  occur  in  some  of  the 
tribes  having  a  system  of  Omaha  type.  Though  there  has  been  no 
marriage  of  this  kind  in  the  Fox  tribe  in  recent  times  it  is  spoken 
of  as  a  custom  that  formerly  existed.  We  have  seen  that  the  marriage 
custom  and  the  terminology  fit  consistently.  The  reason  for  this 
should  now  be  easy  to  understand,  for  a  little  consideration  will 
show  that  this  particular  marriage  is  an  application  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  the  unity  of  the  lineage  combined  with  the  custom  of  the 
sororate  or  sororal  polygyny.  In  the  usual  form  of  these  customs 
we  are  concerned  only  with  the  principle  of  the  unity  of  the 
sibling  group.  A  man  marries  one  woman  of  a  particular  sibling 
group  and  thereby  establishes  a  particular  relation  to  that  group 
as  a  unity.  The  men  are  now  permanently  his  brothers-in-law. 
Towards  one  of  the  women  he  stands  in  a  marital  relationship,  and 
therefore  towards  the  others  he  is  conceived  as  standing  in  a 
similar  relationship  which  may  be  called  a  quasi-marital  relation- 
ship. For  instance,  they  will  regard  his  children  as  being  their 
'children'.  Thus  it  is  appropriate  that  when  he  takes  a  second  wife, 
whether  before  or  after  the  death  of  his  first,  he  should  marry 
his  wife's  sister. 

I  am  quite  aware  that  sororal  polygyny  can  be  attributed 
to  the  fact  that  co-wives  who  are  sisters  are  less  likely  to  quarrel 
seriously  than  two  who  are  not  so  related,  and  that  the  sororate 
may  similarly  be  justified  by  the  fact  that  a  stepmother  is  more 
likely  to  have  proper  affection  for  her  stepchildren  if  they  are  the 


THE   STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  8 1 

children  of  her  own  sister.  These  propositions  do  not  conflict 
with  my  explanation  but  support  it,  for  the  principle  of  the 
unity  of  the  sibling  group  as  a  structural  principle  is  based  on  the 
solidarity  of  brothers  and  sisters  within  one  family. 

When  we  turn  to  systems  of  the  Omaha  type,  we  see  that  in 
place  of  the  unity  of  the  sibling  group  we  now  have  a  unity  of  the 
larger  group,  the  lineage  group  of  three  generations.  When  a  man 
marries  one  woman  of  this  group  he  enters  into  a  relation  with  the 
group  as  a  unity,  so  that  all  the  men  are  now  his  brothers-in-law% 
and  he  at  the  same  time  enters  into  what  I  have  called  a  quasi- 
marital  relationship  with  all  the  women,  including  not  only  his 
wife's  sisters  but  also  his  wife's  brother's  daughters,  and  in  some 
systems  his  wife's  father's  sisters.  The  group  within  which,  by  the 
principle  of  the  sororate,  he  may  take  a  second  wife  without  enter- 
ing into  any  new  social  bonds  is  thus  extended  to  include  his  wife's 
brother's  daughter;  and  the  custom  of  marriage  with  this  relative 
is  simply  the  result  of  the  application  of  the  principle  of  the  unity 
of  the  lineage  in  a  system  of  patrilineal  lineages.  The  special  form 
of  marriage  and  the  special  system  of  terminology,  where  they 
occur  together,  are  directly  connected  by  the  fact  that  they  are 
both  applications  of  the  one  structural  principle.  There  is  no 
ground  whatever  for  supposing  that  one  is  the  historical  cause  of 
the  other. 

The  matter  is  much  more  complex  when  we  come  to  the  custom 
of  marriage  with  the  mother's  brother's  widow.  This  form  of 
marriage  is  found  associated  with  terminology  of  the  Choctaw 
type  in  the  Banks  Islands,  in  the  tribes  of  North-West  America 
and  in  the  Twi-speaking  Akim  Abuakwa.  But  it  is  also  found  in 
many  other  places  w  here  that  type  of  terminology  does  not  exist. 
Nor  is  it  correlated  with  matrilineal  descent,  for  it  is  to  be  found 
in  African  societies  that  are  markedly  patrilineal  in  their  institutions. 
There  does  not  seem  to  be  any  theoretical  explanation  that  will 
apply  to  all  the  known  instances  of  this  custom.  There  is  no  time 
on  this  occasion  to  discuss  this  subject  by  an  analysis  of  instances. 

I  must  briefly  refer  to  another  theory,  which  goes  back  to 
Durkheim's  review  (1898)  of  Kohler,  and  by  which  the  Choctaw 
and  Omaha  terminologies  are  explained  as  being  the  direct 
result  of  emphasis  on  matrilineal  and  patrilineal  descent  respec- 
tively. We  have,  fortunately,  a  crucial  instance  to  which  we  can 
refer  in  this  connection,  in  the  system  of  the  Manus  of  the 


82  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN  PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

Admiralty  Islands,  of  which  we  have  an  excellent  analysis  by  Dr. 
Margaret  Mead  (1934).  The  most  important  feature  of  the  Manus 
system  is  the  existence  of  patrilineal  clans  (called  by  Dr.  Mead 
'gentes')  and  the  major  emphasis  is  on  patrilineal  descent.  The 
solidarity  of  the  patrilineal  lineage  is  exhibited  in  many  features 
of  the  system,  but  not  in  the  terminology.  However  this  emphasis 
on  patrilineal  descent  is  to  a  certain  extent  counterbalanced  by  the 
recognition  of  matrilineal  lineages,  and  this  does  appear  in  the 
terminology  in  features  that  make  it  similar  to  the  Choctaw  type. 
Thus  a  single  term,  pinpapu,  is  applied  to  the  father's  father's 
sister  and  to  all  her  female  descendants  in  the  female  line,  and  a 
single  term,  patieyCy  is  applied  to  the  father's  sister  and  all  her 
descendants  in  the  female  line.  The  unity  of  the  matrilineal 
lineage  is  exhibited  not  only  in  the  use  of  these  terms,  but  also 
in  the  general  social  relation  in  which  a  person  stands  to  the 
members  of  it,  and  is  an  important  feature  of  the  total  complex 
kinship  structure. 

One  of  the  strange  ideas  that  has  been,  and  I  fear  still  is, 
current  is  that  if  a  society  recognises  lineage  at  all  it  can  only 
recognise  either  patrilineal  or  matrilineal  lineage.  I  believe  the 
origin  of  this  absurd  notion,  and  its  persistence  in  the  face  of 
known  facts,  are  the  result  of  that  early  hypothesis  of  conjectural 
history  that  matrilineal  descent  is  more  primitive,  i.e.  historically 
earlier,  than  patrilineal  descent.  From  the  beginning  of  this  century 
we  have  been  acquainted  with  societies,  such  as  the  Herero,  in 
which  both  matrilineal  and  patrilineal  lineages  are  recognised; 
but  these  were  dismissed  as  being  'transitional'  forms.  This  is 
another  example  of  the  way  in  which  attachment  to  the  method 
and  hypotheses  of  conjectural  history  prevents  us  from  seeing 
things  as  they  are.  It  was  this,  I  think,  that  was  responsible  for 
Rivers'  failing  to  discover  that  the  Toda  system  recognises 
matrilineal  lineage  as  well  as  patrilineal,  and  that  the  islands  of 
the  New  Hebrides  have  a  system  of  patriUneal  groups  in  addition 
to  their  matrilineal  moieties.  Apart  from  the  presuppositions  of  the 
method  of  conjectural  history,  there  is  no  reason  why  a  society 
should  not  build  its  kinship  system  on  the  basis  of  both  patriUneal 
and  matrilineal  lineage,  and  we  know  that  there  are  many  societies 
that  do  exactly  this. 

In  my  criticism  of  the  method  of  conjectural  history  I  have 
insisted  on  the  need  for  demonstration  in  anthropology.  How  then 


THE   STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  83 

am  I  to  demonstrate  that  my  interpretation  of  the  Choctaw- 
Omaha  terminologies  is  the  vaUd  one?  There  are  a  number  of 
possible  arguments,  but  I  have  time  for  only  one,  which  I  hope  may 
be  considered  sufficient.  This  is  drawn  from  the  existence  of 
terminologies  in  which  the  unity  of  lineage  or  clan  is  exhibited, 
but  which  do  not  belong  to  either  the  Choctaw  or  the  Omaha  type; 
and  I  will  mention  one  example,  that  of  the  Yaralde  tribe  of 
South  Australia. 

The  Yaralde  are  divided  into  local  patrilineal  totemic  clans. 
A  man  belongs  to  his  father's  clan,  and  we  will  consider  his 
relation  to  three  other  clans:  those  of  his  mother,  his  father's 
mother  and  his  mother's  mother.  The  Yaralde,  like  many  other 
Australian  tribes,  such  as  the  Aranda,  have  four  terms  for  grand- 
parents, each  of  which  is  applied  to  both  men  and  women. 
The  term  maty  a  is  applied  to  the  father's  father  and  his  brothers 
and  sisters  and  to  all  members  of  a  man's  own  clan  of  the  second 
ascending  generation.  A  second  term,  Tjaitja,  is  applied  to  the 
mother's  father  and  his  brothers  and  sisters,  i.e.  to  persons  of  the 
mother's  clan  of  the  appropriate  generation.  The  third  term, 
mutsa,  is  applied  not  only  to  the  father's  mother  and  her  brothers 
and  sisters,  but  to  all  persons  belonging  to  the  same  clan,  of  all 
generations  and  of  both  sexes.  The  clan  is  spoken  of  collectively 
as  a  man's  mut^aurui.  Similarly  the  term  haka  is  applied  to  the 
mother's  mother  and  her  brothers  and  sisters  and  to  all  members 
of  her  clan  of  all  generations,  the  clan  being  spoken  of  as  a 
man's  hakaurui.  The  structural  principle  here  is  that  for  the  out- 
side related  person  the  clan  constitutes  a  unity  within  which 
distinctions  of  generation  are  obliterated.  Compare  this  with  the 
treatment  of  lineages  or  clans  of  grandparents  in  the  Fox,  Hopi 
and  Cherokee  systems. 

The  Yaralde  terminology  for  relatives  in  the  mother's  clan  is 
shown  in  Fig.  13.  It  will  be  noted  that  the  mother's  brother's  son 
and  daughter  are  not  called  mother's  brother  {wano)  and  mother 
{fierjko)  as  in  Omaha  systems.  But  the  son's  son  and  daughter  of 
the  mother's  brother  are  called  'mother's  brother'  and  'mother'. 
If  we  wish  to  explain  this  by  a  special  form  of  marriage  it  would 
have  to  be  marriage  with  the  wife's  brother's  son's  daughter. 
I  am  not  certain  that  such  a  marriage  would  be  prohibited  by  the 
Yaralde  system,  but  I  am  quite  sure  that  it  is  not  a  custom  so 
regular  as  to  be  regarded  as  an  effective  cause  in  producing  the 


84  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

Yaralde  terininology,  and  it  would  afford  no  explanation  whatever 
for  the  terminological  unification  of  the  clans  of  the  father's 
mother  and  the  mother's  mother.  The  structural  principle  in- 
volved is  obviously  that  of  the  merging  of  alternate  generations, 
which  is  of  such  great  importance  in  Australia,  and  which  we  have 
also  seen  in  the  Hopi  system.  A  system  very  similar  to  the  Yaralde 


A 

tfaitja 

mother's  father 


O. 
-rjaitja 
mother's  father's  sister 


A 
zoano 
mother's  brother 


O 

nerjko 

mother 


A 
Tjuya 
mother's  brother's  son 


O 

■quya 

mother's  brother's  daughter 


A 
tvano 
mother's  brother's 
son's  son 


O 
neriko 


A 
Tjuya 


Tjaitja) 

ne7)ko  f-i)  IS  ng 
T]uya 


O 

■quya 


Fig.  13 — Yaralde 
Mother's  hneage 


is  found  in  the  Ungarinyin  tribe  of  North- West  Australia,  but  I 
will  not  do  more  than  refer  to  it. 

Earlier  in  this  address  I  said  that  I  would  try  to  show  you  that 
the  Omaha  type  of  terminology  is  just  as  reasonable  and  fitting 
in  those  social  systems  in  which  it  is  found  as  our  own  terminology 
is  in  our  system,  I  hope  I  have  succeeded  in  doing  this.  On  the 
basis  of  the  elementary  family  and  the  genealogical  relationships 
resulting  therefrom,  we  English  have  constructed  for  ourselves  a 
certain  kinship  system  which  meets  the  necessities  of  an  ordered 
social  life  and  is  fairly  self-consistent.  The  Fox  or  the  Hopi  have 
on  the  same  basis  constructed  a  relatively  self-consistent  system 


THE   STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  85 

of  a  different  type  which  provides  for  the  needs  of  social  cohesion 
in  a  different  way  and  over  a  wider  range.  We  understand  the 
terminology  in  each  instance  as  soon  as  we  see  it  as  part  of  an 
ordered  system.  The  obvious  connection  of  the  Omaha  termino- 
logy with  the  custom  of  marriage  with  the  wife's  brother's 
daughter  is  seen  as  a  relation  between  two  parts  of  a  self- consistent 
working  system,  not  as  a  relation  of  cause  and  effect. 

If  you  ask  the  question,  'How^  is  it  that  the  Omaha  (or  any 
other  of  the  tribes  we  have  considered)  have  the  system  that  they 
do?'  then  it  is  obvious  that  the  method  of  structural  analysis  does 
not  afford  an  answer.  But  neither  does  conjectural  history.  The 
proffered  but  purely  hypothetical  explanation  of  the  Omaha 
terminology  is  that  it  resulted  from  the  adoption  of  a  certain 
unusual  custom  of  marriage.  This  obviously  gives  us  no  explanation 
until  we  know  why  the  Omaha  and  other  tribes  came  to  adopt  this 
custom.  The  only  possible  wa}^  of  answering  the  question  why  a 
particular  society  has  the  social  system  that  it  does  have  is  by  a 
detailed  study  of  its  history  over  a  sufficient  period,  generally 
several  centuries.  For  the  tribes  with  which  we  are  here  concerned 
the  materials  for  such  a  history  are  entirely  lacking.  This  is,  of 
course,  very  regrettable,  but  there  is  nothing  that  v,'e  can  do  about 
it.  If  you  want  to  know  how  England  comes  to  have  its  present 
system  of  constitutional  monarchy  and  parliamentary  government, 
you  will  go  to  the  history  books,  which  will  give  you  the  details  of 
the  growth  of  the  system.  If  there  were  no  records  at  all  of  this 
historical  development,  would  the  anthropologists  think  it  worth 
while  to  spend  their  time  in  making  conjectures  as  to  what  it 
might  have  been? 

Even  when  there  are  historical  records,  they  only  enable  us 
to  discover  how  a  particular  system  has  grown  out  of  a  somewhat 
different  particular  system.  Thus  it  would  be  possible  to  write  a 
historical  account  of  the  changes  of  the  kinship  system  of  England 
during  the  past  ten  centuries.  This  would  take  us  back  to  the 
Teutonic  bilateral  sib  system,  as  exhibited  in  the  institution  of 
wergild.  But  we  still  should  not  know  why  the  Teutonic  peoples 
had  this  kind  of  system,  while  the  Romans  had  a  different  system 
of  agnatic  lineages.  The  great  value  of  history  for  a  science  of 
society  is  that  it  gives  us  materials  for  the  study  of  how  social 
systems  change.  In  this  respect  conjectural  history  is  absolutely 
worthless. 


86  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

But  if  you  ask,  not  how  the  EngHsh  kinship ,  system  or  the 
EngUsh  political  system  came  into  existence,  but  how  it  works  at 
the  present  time,  that  is  a  question  that  can  be  answered  by 
research  of  the  same  kind  as  anthropological  field-work,  and  his- 
torical considerations  are  relatively,  if  not  absolutely,  unimportant. 
Such  knowledge  of  how  social  systems  work  is  of  great  value 
for  any  understanding  of  human  life.  It  often  has  been  and  still 
is  neglected  by  anthropologists  who  consider  it  their  principal 
task  to  write  the  history  of  peoples  or  institutions  that  have  no 
history. 

If  you  accept  the  analysis  that  I  have  given,  but  still  wish  to 
apply  the  method  of  conjectural  history,  what  you  have  to  con- 
jecture is  why  all  the  tribes  that  have  been  enumerated  elected 
to  construct  their  kinship  systems  on  the  basis  of  the  unity  of 
the  lineage. 

What  kind  of  results  can  we  expect  to  obtain  from  the  method 
of  sociological  analysis?  Nothing,  of  course,  that  will  be  accept- 
able as  significant  by  those  who  demand  that  any  explanation 
of  a  social  phenomenon  must  be  a  historical  explanation,  or  by 
those  who  demand  what  is  called  psychological  explanation,  i.e. 
explanation  in  terms  of  the  individual  and  his  motives.  I  suggest 
that  the  results  that  we  may  reasonably  expect  are  as  follows: 

1.  It  will  enable  us  to  make  a  systematic  classification  of 
kinship  systems.  Systematic  classification  is  an  essential 
in  any  scientific  treatment  of  any  class  of  phenomena, 
and  such  classification  must  be  in  terms  of  general  properties. 

2.  It  enables  us  to  understand  particular  features  of  par- 
ticular systems.  It  does  this  in  tw^o  ways:  (a)  by  revealing 
the  particular  feature  as  a  part  of  an  organised  whole; 
{b)  by  showing  that  it  is  a  special  example  of  a  recognisable 
class  of  phenomena.  Thus  I  have  tried  to  show  that  the 
Choctaw  and  Omaha  terminologies  belong  to  a  class  w'hich 
also  includes  the  Yaralde  terminology,  and  that  these  are 
all  special  applications  of  the  general  principle  of  the 
solidarity  and  continuity  of  the  lineage,  which  appears  in 
many  other  forms  in  a  great  number  of  different  societies. 

3.  It  is  the  only  method  by  which  we  can  hope  ultimately 
to  arrive  at  valid  generalisations  about  the  nature  of  human 
society,  i.e.  about  the  universal  characteristics  of  all 
societies,  past,  present,  and  future.  It  is,  of  course,  such 


THE  STUDY  OF  KINSHIP  SYSTEMS  87 

generalisations  that  are  meant  when  we  speak  of  sociological 
laws. 

In  the  method  of  conjectural  history  single  problems  are 
usually  considered  in  isolation.  On  the  other  hand,  the  method 
of  structural  analysis  aims  at  a  general  theory,  and  a  great  many 
different  facts  and  problems  are,  therefore,  considered  together 
and  in  relation  to  one  another.  It  is  obvious  that  in  this  address, 
inordinately  long  as  it  has  been,  I  have  only  been  able  to  touch  on 
a  few  points  in  the  general  theory  of  kinship  structure.  I  have 
dealt  briefly  with  one  or  two  other  points  in  earlier  publications. 
That  particular  part  of  the  general  theory  which  has  occupied 
us  today  may  be  said  to  be  the  theory  of  the  establishment  of 
type  relationships.  I  have  mentioned  the  tendency  present  in 
many  societies  to  set  up  a  type  relationship  betw^een  a  person  and 
all  his  relatives  of  the  parents'  generation,  and  the  even  more 
marked  tendency  to  establish  a  type  relationship,  usually  one  of 
free  and  easy  behaviour,  towards  the  relatives  of  the  grandparents' 
generation.  I  have  not  tried  to  deal  with  this  except  incidentally. 
The  major  part  of  the  exposition  has  been  concerned  with  tv^^o 
structural  principles  which  are  themselves  examples  of  a  more 
general  structural  principle  or  class  of  principles.!  By  the  principle 
of  the  unity  of  the  sibling  group  a  type  relationship  is  set  up 
between  a  given  person  and  all  the  members  of  a  sibling  group  to 
which  he  is  related  in  a  certain  way.  It  is  by  reference  to  this 
principle,  I  hold,  that  we  must  interpret  the  classificatojy  ter- 
minology and  such  customs  as  the  sororate  and  levirate.|By  the 
principle  of  the  unity  of  the  lineage  group  a  type  relationship  is  set 
up  between  a  given  person  and  all  the  members  of  a  lineage  group 
to  which  he  is  related  in  a  certain  way.  It  is  by  reference  to  this 
principle,  I  hold,  that  we  must  interpret  the  terminologies  of  the 
Fox,  the  Hopi  and  the  Yaralde,  and  other  similar  systems  in  many 
scattered  parts  of  the  world. 

If  you  will  take  the  time  to  study  two  or  three  hundred 
kinship  systems  from  all  parts  of  the  world  you  will  be  impressed, 
I  think,  by  the  great  diversity  that  they  exhibit.  But  you  will  also 
be  impressed  by  the  way  in  which  some  particular  feature,  such 
as  an  Omaha  type  of  terminology,  reappears  in  scattered  and  widely 
spread  regions.  To  reduce  this  diversity  to  some  sort  of  order 
is  the  task  of  analysis,  and  by  its  means  we  can,  I  believe,  find, 
beneath  the  diversities,  a  limited  number  of  general  principles 


88  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

applied  and  combined  in  various  ways.  Lineage  solidarity  in  one 
form  or  another  is  found  in  a  majority  of  kinship  systems.  There 
is  nothing  at  all  surprising  in  the  fact  that  terminologies  of  the 
Choctaw  and  Omaha  type,  in  which  it  finds  what  may  be  called 
an  extreme  development,  should  be  encountered  in  separated 
regions  of  America,  Africa,  Asia  and  Oceania,  in  many  different 
families  of  languages,  and  in  association  with  many  different 
types  of  'culture'. 

Last  year  I  explained  in  general  terms  how  I  conceive  the 
study  of  social  structure  (Radcliffe-Brown,  19406).  In  this  address, 
by  means  of  a  particular  example,  I  have  tried  to  show  you  some- 
thing of  the  nature  of  a  certain  method  of  investigation.  But  do 
not  think  that  this  method  can  be  applied  only  to  the  study  of 
kinship.  It  is  applicable  in  one  way  or  another  to  all  social 
phenomena,  for  it  is  simply  the  method  of  abstractive  generalisa- 
tion by  the  comparison  of  instances,  which  is  the  characteristic 
method  of  the  inductive  sciences. 

'Why  all  this  fuss  about  method?'  some  of  you  may  perhaps 
ask.  We  cannot  reach  agreement  as  to  the  validity  or  the  value  of 
results  unless  we  first  reach  some  agreement  as  to  objectives  and 
the  proper  methods  of  attaining  them.  In  the  other  natural 
sciences  there  is  such  agreement;  in  social  anthropology  there  is  not. 
Where  we  disagree,  it  should  be  the  first  purpose  of  discussion  to 
define  as  precisely  as  possible  the  ground  of  difference.  I  have 
put  my  case  before  you,  without,  I  hope,  any  unfairness  towards 
those  with  whom  I  disagree.  It  is  for  you  to  judge  which  of  the  two 
methods  that  I  have  compared  is  most  likely  to  provide  that  kind 
of  scientific  understanding  of  the  nature  of  human  society  which 
it  is  the  accepted  task  of  the  social  anthropologist  to  provide  for 
the  guidance  of  mankind. 

REFERENCES 

Durkheim,  E.  (1898).  'Zur  Urgeschichte  der   Ehe,    Prof.   J.    Kohler', 

Analyses  III,  La  Famille,  Annee  Sociologique,  Vol.  I,  pp.  306-319. 
Eggan,  F.  (1933).  'The  Kinship  System  and  Social  Organisation  of  the 

Western  Pueblos  with  Special  Reference  to  the  Hopi',  Ph.D.  thesis, 

University  of  Chicago. 
GiflFord,  E.  W.  (1916).  'Miwok  Moieties',  Arch,  mid  Ethn.  Piibl.,  Univ. 

California,  Vol.  XII,  No.  4. 
Gilbert,  William  H.,  Jr.  (1937).  'Eastern  Cherokee  Social  Organisation', 

in  Social  Anthropology  of  North  American  Tribes  (ed.  Fred  Eggan). 

Chicago  University  Press,  pp.  283-338. 


THE   STUDY   OF   KINSHIP   SYSTEMS  89 

Kohler,  J.  (1897).  'Zur  Urgeschichte  der  Ehe',  Zeitschrift  filr  Vergleichende 

Rechtswissenschaft  (Stuttgart),  Bd.  11. 
Kroeber,    A.    L.    (1909).     'Classificatory    Systems    of    Relationship', 

J.  R.  Anthrop.  Inst.,  Vol.  XXXIX,  pp.  77-84. 

—  (1917).  'California  Kinship  Systems',  Arch,  and  Ethn.  Puhl.  Univ. 
California,  Vol.  XII,  No.  9. 

Mead,  Margaret  (1934).  'Kinship  in  the  Admiralty  Islands',  Anthrop. 

Papas  Amer.  Mus.  Nat.  History,  Vol.  XXXIV,  Pt.  II,  pp.  181-358. 
M'Lennan,  John  F.  (1865).  Primitive  Marriage.  Edinburgh:  Adam  & 

Charles  Black. 
Morgan,  Lewis  H.  (1871).  'The  Systems  of  Consanguinity  and  Affinity', 

Smithsofiian    Institution    Contributions    to   Knozvledge,   Vol.    XVII. 

—  (1877).  Ancient  Society  or  Researches  in  the  Lines  of  Human  Progress 
from  Savagery  to  Civilisation.  London:  Macmillan;  New  York: 
Henry  Holt. 

Opler,  M.  E.  (19370).  'Chiricahua  Apache  Social  Organisation',  in  Social 
Anthropology  of  North  American  Tribes  (ed.  Fred  Eggan),  Chicago 
University  Press. 

—  (19376).  'Apache  Data  Concerning  the  Relation  of  Kinship  Ter- 
minology to  Social  Classification',  Amer.  Anthrop.,  Vol.  XXXIX, 
pp.  201-212. 

Radcliffe-Brown,  A.  R.  (1918).  'Notes  on  the  Social  Organisation  of 
Australian  Tribes',  Pt.  I,  J.  R.  Anthrop.  Inst.,  Vol.  XLVIII, 
pp.  222-253. 

—  (1924).  'The  Mother's  Brother  in  South  Africa',  South  African 
y.  Science,  Vol.  XXI. 

—  (1930-31).  'The  Social  Organisation  of  Australian  Tribes',  Pts.  I-III, 
Oceania,  Vol.  I,  pp.  34-63,  206-246,  322-341,  426-456. 

—  (1935).  'Patrilineal  and  Matrilineal  Succession',  Iowa  Law  Review, 
Vol.  XX,  No.  2. 

—  (1940a).  'On  Joking  Relationships',  Africa,  Vol.  XIII,  No.  3, 
pp.  195-210. 

—  (19406).  'On  Social  Structure',  J.  R.  Anthrop.  Inst.,  Vol.  LXX, 
pp.  1-12. 

Rivers,  W.  H.  R.  (1907).  'On  the  Origin  of  the  Classificatory  System  of 
Relationship',  in  Anthropological  Essays  Presented  to  Edward  Burnett 
Tylor.  Oxford:  Clarendon  Press.  (Reprinted  in  Social  Organisation. 
London:  Kegan  Paul,  1924,  App.  i,  pp.  175-192.) 

—  (1914a).  History  of  Melanesian  Society.  Cambridge  University  Press. 

—  (19146).  Kinship  and  Social  Organisation.  London:  London  School  of 
Economics. 

Seligman,   Brenda  Z.  (1917).  'The  Relationship  Systems  of  the  Nandi 

Masai  and  Thonga',  Man,  Vol.  XVII,  46. 
Starcke,  C.  N.  (1889).  The  Primitive  Family  (The  International  Scientific 

Series,  Vol.  LXVI).  London:  Kegan  Paul. 
Stewart,  Dugald  (1795).  Introduction  to  Essays  of  Adam  Smith. 
Tax,  Sol  (1937).  'The  Social  Organisation  of  the  Fox  Indians',  in  Social 

Anthropology  of  North  American  Tribes  (ed.  Fred  Eggan).  Chicago 

University  Press,  pp.  241-282. 


CHAPTER     IV 

ON  JOKING   RELATIONSHIPS! 

THE  publication  of  Mr.  F.  J.  Pedler's  note^  on  what  are 
called  'joking  relationships',  following  on  two  other  papers 
on  the  same  subject  by  Professor  Henri  Labouret^ 
and  Mademoiselle  Denise  Paulme,*  suggests  that  some  general 
theoretical  discussion  of  the  nature  of  these  relationships  may  be 
of  interest  to  readers  of  Africa.^ 

What  is  meant  by  the  term  'joking  relationship'  is  a  relation 
between  two  persons  in  which  one  is  by  custom  permitted,  and  in 
some  instances  required,  to  tease  or  make  fun  of  the  other,  who  in 
turn  is  required  to  take  no  offence.  It  is  important  to  distinguish 
[  two  main  varieties.  In  one  the  relation  is  symmetrical;  each  of  the 
two  persons  teases  or  makes  fun  of  the  other.  In  the  other  variety 
the  relation  is  asymmetrical;  A  jokes  at  the  expense  of  B  and  B 
accepts  the  teasing  good  humouredly  but  without  retaliating;  or 
A  teases  B  as  much  as  he  pleases  and  B  in  return  teases  A  only  a 
little.  There  are  many  varieties  in  the  form  of  this  relationship  in 
different  societies.  In  some  instances  the  joking  or  teasing  is  only 
verbal,  in  others  it  includes  horse-play;  in  some  the  joking 
includes  elements  of  obscenity,  in  others  not. 

Standardised  social  relationships  of  this  kind  are  extremely 

C widespread,  not  only  in  Africa  but  also  in  Asia,  Oceania  and 
North  America.  To  arrive  at  a  scientific  understanding  of  the 
phenomenon  it  is  necessary  to  make  a  wide  comparative  study. 
Some  material  for  this  now  exists  in  anthropological  literature, 
though  by  no  means  all  that  could  be  desired,  since  it  is  un- 
fortunately still  only  rarely  that  such  relationships  are  observed 
and  described  as  exactly  as  they  might  be. 

^  Reprinted  from  Africa,  Vol.  XIII,  No.  3,  1940,  pp.  195-210. 

^  'Joking  Relationships  in  East  Africa',  Africa,  Vol.  XIII,  p.  170. 

^  'La  Parent^  a  Plaisanteries  en  Afrique  Occidentale',  Africa,  Vol.  II,  p.  244. 

*  'Parent^  a  Plaisanteries  et  Alliance  par  le  Sang  en  Afrique  Occidentale', 
Africa,  Vol.  XII,  p.  433. 

^  Professor  Marcel  Mauss  has  published  a  brief  theoretical  discussion  of  the 
subject  in  the  Annuaire  de  VEcole  Pratique  des  Hautes  Etudes,  Section  des 
Sciences  religietises ,  1927-8.  It  is  also  dealt  with  by  Dr.  F.  Eggan  in  Social 
Anthropology  of  North  American  Tribes,  1937,  pp.  75-81. 

90 


ON  JOKING  RELATIONSHIPS  9 1 

The  joking  relationship  is  a  pecuHar  combination  of  friendliness 
and  antagonism-  The  behaviour  is^  such  that  in  any  other  social 
context  it  would  express  and  arouse  hostility;  but  it  is  not  meant 
seriously  and  must  not  be  taken  seriously.  There  is  a  pretence  of 
hostility  and  a  real  friendliness.  To  put  it  in  another  way,  the 
relationship  is  one  of  j3ermitted_^isrespect.  Thus  any  complete 
theory  of  it  must  be  part  of,  or  consistent  with,  a  theory  of  the  place 
of  resp^ect  in^spcial  relations  and  in  social  life  generally.  But  this  is^.. 
a  very  wide  and  very  important  sociological  problem;  for  it  is    / 
evident  that  the  whole  maintenance  of  a  social  order  depends  upon  / 
the  appropriate  kind  and  degree  of  respect  being  shown  towards  I 
certain  persons,  things  and  ideas  or  symbols. 

Examples  of  joking  relationships  between  relatives  by  marriage  . 
are  very  commonly  found  in  Africa  and  in  other  parts  of  the  world. 
Thus  Mademoiselle  Paulme^  records  that  among  the  Dogon  a 
man  stands  in  a  joking  relationship  to  his  wife's  sisters  and  their 
daughters.  Frequently  the  relationship  holds  betw'een  a  man  and 
both  the  brothers  and  sisters  of  his  wife.  But  in  some  instances 
there  is  a  distinction  whereby  a  man  is  on  joking  terms  with  his 
wife's  younger  brothers  and  sisters  but  not  with  those  who  are 
older  than  she  is.  This  joking  with  the  wife's  brothers  and  sisters 
is  usually  associated  with  a  custom  requiring  extreme  respect, 
often  partial  or  complete  avoidance,  between  a  son-in-law  and  his 
wife's  parents.  2 

The  kind  of  structural  situation  in  which  the  associated 
customs  of  joking  and  avoidance  are  found  may  be  described  as 
follows.  A  marriage  involves  a  readjustment  of  the  social  struc-  _-n 
.ture  whereby  the  woman's  relations  with  her  family  are  greatly  < 
modified  and  she  enters  into  a  new  and  very  close  relation  with  her 
husband.  The  latter  is  at  the  same  time  brought  into  a  special 
relation  with  his  wife's  family,  to  which,  however,  he  is  an  outsider. 
For  the  sake  of  brevity,  though  at  the  risk  of  over-simplification, 
we  will  consider  only  the  husband's  relation  to  his  wife's  family. 
The  relation  can  be  c'escribed  as  involving  both  attachment  and 
separation,  both  social  conjunction  and  social  disjunction,  if  I 

1  Africa,  Vol.  XII,  p.  438. 

^  Those  who  are  not  familiar  with  these  widespread  customs  will  find  descrip- 
tions in  Junod,  Life  of  a  South  African  Tribe,  NeuchStel,  Vol.  I,  pp.  229-37,  ^nd 
in  Social  Aytthropology  of  North  American  Tribes,  edited  by  F.  Eggan,  Chicago, 
1937,  PP-  55-7- 


92  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

may  use  the  terms.  The  man  has  his  own  definite  position  in  the 
social  structure,  determined  for  him  by  his  birth  into  a  certain 
family,  Hneage  or  clan.  The  great  body  of  his  rights  and  duties  and 
the  interests  and  activities  that  he  shares  with  others  are  the  result 
of  his  position.  Before  the  marriage  his  wife's  family  are  outsiders 
for  him  as  he  is  an  outsider  for  them.  This  constitutes  a  social 
disjunction  which  is  not  destroyed  by  the  marriage.  The  social 
conjunction  results  from  the  continuance,  though  in  altered  form, 
of  the  wife's  relation  to  her  family,  their  continued  interest  in  her 
and  in  her  children.  If  the  wife  were  really  bought  and  paid  for, 
as  ignorant  persons  say  that  she  is  in  Africa,  there  would  be  ho 
place  for  any  permanent  close  relation  of  a  man  with  his  w^ife's 
family.  But  though  slaves  can  be  bought,  wives  cannot. 

Social  disjunction  implies  divergence  of  interests  and  therefore 
the  possibility  of  conflict  and  hostility,  while  conjunction  requires 
the  avoidance  of  strife.  How  can  a  relation  which  combines  the 
)<^'~~  two  be  given  a  stable,  ordered  form?  There  are  two  ways  of  doing 
this.  One  is  to  maintain  between  two  persons  so  related  an  extreme 
mutual  respect  and  a  limitation  of  direct  personal  contact.  This  is 
exhibited  in  the  very  formal  relations  that  are,  in  so  many  societies, 
characteristic  of  the  behaviour  of  a  son-in  law  on  the  one  side  and 

this  wife's  father  and  mother  on  the  other.  In  its  most  extreme  form 
there  is  complete  avoidance  of  any  social  contact  between  a  man 
and  his  mother-in-law. 

This  avoidance  must  not  be  mistaken  for  a  sign  of  hostility. 

One  does,  of  course,  if  one  is  wise,  avoid  having  too  much  to  do 

with  one's  enemies,  but  that  is  quite  a  different  matter.  I  once 

asked  an  Australian  native  why  he  had  to  avoid  his  mother-in-law, 

and  his  reply  was,  'Because  she  is  my  best  friend  in  the  world;  she 

r  has  given  me  my  wife'.  The  mutual  respect  between  son-in-law 

\  and  parents-in-law  is  a  mode  of  friendship.  It  prevents  conflict 

\  that  might  arise  through  divergence  of  interest. 

;       The  alternative  to  this  relation  of  extreme  mutual  respect  and 

V  /restraint  is  the  joking  relationship,  one,  that  is,  of  mutual  dis- 

~^    respect  and  licence.  Any  serious  hostility  is  prevented  by  the 

playful  antagonism  of  teasing,  and  this  in  its  regular  repetition  is 

a  constant  expression  or  reminder  of  that  social  disjunction  which 

is  one  of  the  essential  components  of  the  relation,  while  the  social 

conjunction   is    maintained   by   the   friendliness   that   takes    no 

offence  at  insult. 


ON  JOKING   RELATIONSHIPS  93 

The  discrimination  within  the  wife's  family  between  those 
who  have  to  be  treated  with  extreme  respect  and  those  with 
whom  it  is  a  duty  to  be  disrespectful  is  made  on  the  basis  of 
generation  and  sometimes  of  seniority  within  the  generation. 
The  usual  respected  relatives  are  those  of  the  first  ascending 
generation,  the  wife's  mother  and  her  sisters,  the  wife's  father 
and  his  brothers,  sometimes  the  wife's  mother's  brother.  The 
joking  relatives  are  those  of  a  person's  own  generation;  but  very 
frequently  a  distinction  of  seniority  within  the  generation  is  made; 
a  wife's  older  sister  or  brother  may  be  respected  while  those 
younger  will  be  teased. 

In  certain  societies  a  man  may  be  said  to  have  relatives  by 
marriage  long  before  he  marries  and  indeed  as  soon  as  he  is  born 
into  the  world.  This  is  provided  by  the  institution  of  the  required 
or  preferential  marriage.  We  will,  for  the  sake  of  brevity,  consider 
only  one  kind  of  such  organisations.  In  many  societies  it  is  re- 
garded as  preferable  that  a  man  should  marry  the  daughter  of 
his  mother's  brother;  this  is  a  form  of  the  custom  known  as  cross- 
cousin  marriage.  Thus  his  female  cousins  of  this  kind,  or  all  those 
women  whom  by  the  classificatory  system  he  classifies  as  such, 
are  potential  wives  for  him,  and  their  brothers  are  his  potential 
brothers-in-law.  Among  the  Ojibwa  Indians  of  North  America, 
the  Chiga  of  Uganda,  and  in  Fiji  and  New  Caledonia,  as  well  as 
elsewhere,  this  form  of  marriage  is  found  and  is  accompanied  by 
a  joking  relationship  between  a  man  and  the  sons  and  daughters 
of  his  mother's  brother.  To  quote  one  instance  of  these,  the 
following  is  recorded  for  the  Ojibwa.  'When  cross-cousins  meet 
they  must  try  to  embarrass  one  another.  They  "joke"  one  another, 
making  the  most  vulgar  allegations,  by  their  standards  as  well 
as  ours.  But  being  "kind"  relations,  no  one  can  take  oflFence. 
Cross-cousins  who  do  not  joke  in  this  way  are  considered  boorish, 
as  not  playing  the  social  game.'^ 

The  joking  relationship  here  is  of  fundamentally  the  same  kind 
as  that  already  discussed.  It  is  established  before  marriage  and  is 
continued,  after  marriage,  with  the  brothers-  and  sisters-in-law. 

In  some  parts  of  Africa  there  are  joking  relationships  that  have 
nothing  to  do  with  marriage.  Mr.  Pedler's  note,  mentioned  above, 
refers  to  a  joking  relationship  between  two  distinct  tribes,  the 

^  Ruth  Landes  in  Mead,  Co-operation  and  Competition  among  Primitive 
Peoples,  1937,  p.  103. 


94  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

Sukuma  and  the  Zaramu,  and  in  the  evidence  it  was  stated  that 
there  was  a  similar  relation  between  the  Sukuma  and  the  Zigua 
and  between  the  Ngoni  and  the  Bemba.  The  woman's  evidence 
suggests  that  this  custom  of  rough  teasing  exists  in  the  Sukuma 
tribe  between  persons  related  by  marriage,  as  it  does  in  so  many 
other  African  tribes.^ 

While  a  joking  relationship  between  two  tribes  is  apparently 
rare,  and  certainly  deserves,  as  Mr.  Pedler  suggests,  to  be  carefully 
investigated,  a  similar  relationship  between  clans  has  been  observed 
in  other  parts  of  Africa.  It  is  described  by  Professor  Labouret  and 
Mademoiselle  Paulme  in  the  articles  previously  mentioned,  and 
amongst  the  Tallensi  it  has  been  studied  by  Dr.  Fortes,  who  will 
deal  with  it  in  a  forthcoming  publication.  ^ 

The  two  clans  are  not,  in  these  instances,  specially  connected 
by  intermarriage.  The  relation  between  them  is  an  alliance 
involving  real  friendliness  and  mutual  aid  combined  with  an 
appearance  of  hostility. 

The  general  structural  situation  in  these  instances  seems  to  be 
as  follows.  The  individual  is  a  member  of  a  certain  defined  group, 
a  clan,  for  example,  within  which  his  relations  to  others  are 
defined  by  a  complex  set  of  rights  and  duties,  referring  to  all  the 
major  aspects  of  social  life,  and  supported  by  definite  sanctions. 
There  may  be  another  group  outside  his  own  which  is  so  linked 
with  his  as  to  be  the  field  of  extension  of  jural  and  moral  relations 
of  the  same  general  kind.  Thus,  in  East  Africa,  as  we  learn  from 
Mr.  Pedler's  note,  the  Zigua  and  the  Zaramu  do  not  joke  with 
one  another  because  a  yet  closer  bond  exists  between  them  since 
they  are  ndugu  (brothers).  But  beyond  the  field  within  which  social 
relations  are  thus  defined  there  lie  other  groups  with  which,  since 

^  Incidentally  it  may  be  said  that  it  was  hardly  satisfactory  for  the  magistrate 
to  establish  a  precedent  whereby  the  man,  who  was  observing  what  was  a 
permitted  and  may  even  have  been  an  obligatory  custom,  was  declared  guilty  of 
common  assault,  even  with  extenuating  circumstances.  It  seems  quite  possible 
that  the  man  may  have  committed  a  breach  of  etiquette  in  teasing  the  woman 
in  the  presence  of  her  mother's  brother,  for  in  many  parts  of  the  world  it  is 
regarded  as  improper  for  two  persons  in  a  joking  relationship  to  tease  one  another 
(particularly  if  any  obscenity  is  involved)  in  the  presence  of  certain  relatives 
of  either  of  them.  But  the  breach  of  etiquette  would  still  not  make  it  an  assault. 
A  little  knowledge  of  anthropology  would  have  enabled  the  magistrate,  by 
putting  the  appropriate  questions  to  the  witnesses,  to  have  obtained  a  fuller 
understanding  of  the  case  and  all  that  was  involved  in  it. 

^  Fortes,  M.,  The  Dynamics  of  Clanship  among  the  Tallensi.  Oxford  Univer- 
sity Press,  1945. 


ON  JOKING  RELATIONSHIPS  95 

they  are  outsiders  to  the  individual's  own  group,  the  reiationj 
involve^possible  or  actual  hostility..  In  any  fixed  relations  between  > 
the  members  of  two  such  groups  the  separateness  of  the  groups 
must  be  recognised.  It  is  precisely  this  separateness  which  is  not 
merely  recognised  but  emphasised  when  a  joking  relationship  isi 
established.  The  show  of  hostility,  the  perpetual  disrespect,  is  a 
continual  expression  of  that  social  disjunction  which  is  an  essential     ) 
part  of  the  whole  structural  situation,  but  over  which,  without 
destroying  or  even  weakening  it,  there  is  provided  the  social/"     / 
conjunction  of  friendliness  and  mutual  aid.  '      .^ 

The  theory  that  is  here  put  forward,  therefore,  is  that  both  the  '^ 
joking  relationship  which  constitutes  an  alliance  between  clans  or    )    ^ 
tribes,  and  that  between  relatives  by  marriage,  are  modes  of  j   _  , 
organising  a  definite  and  stable  system  of  social  behaviour  in 
which  conjunctive  and  disjunctive  components,  as  I  have  called  ; 
them,  are  maintained  and  combined. 

To  provide  the  full  evidence  for  this  theory  by  following  out 
its  implications  and  examining  in  detail  its  application  to  different 
instances  would  take  a  book  rather  than  a  short  article.  But  some 
confirmation  can  perhaps  be  offered  by  a  consideration  of  the 
way  in  which  respect  and  disrespect  appear  in  various  kinship 
relations,  even  though  nothing  more  can  be  attempted  than  a 
very  brief  indication  of  a  few  significant  points.  "^/' 

In  studying  a  kinship  system  it  is  possible  to  distinguish  the  j 
different  relatives  by  reference  to  the  kind  and  degree  of  respect 
that  is  paid  to  them.^  Although  kinship  systems  vary  very  much  -- ' 
in  their  details  there  are  certain  principles  which  are  found  to  be 
very  widespread.  One  of  them  is  that  by  which  a  person  is  re- 
quired to  show  a  marked  respect  to  relatives  belonging  to  the 
generation  immediately  preceding  his  ow^n.  In  a  majority  of 
societies  the  father  is  a  relative  to  whom  marked  respect  must  be 
shown.  This  is  so  even  in  many  so-called  matrilineal  societies, 
i.e.  those  which  are  organised  into  matrilineal  clans  or  lineages. 
One  can  very  frequently  observe  a  tendency  to  extend  this 
attitude  of  respect  to  all  relatives  of  the  first  ascending  generation 
and,  further,  to  persons  who  are  not  relatives.  Thus  in  those 
Er .!~  <:  p{rc.  r     /c  o  i-    t  -•:  ''■>  ^  "s^?;-  ' 

^  See,  for  example,  the  kinship  systems  described  in  Social  Anthropology  of 
North  American  Tribes,  edited  by  Fred  Eggan,  University  of  Chicago  Press, 
1937;  and  Margaret  Mead,  'Kinship  in  the  Admiralty  Islands',  Anthropological 
Papers  of  the  American  Museum  of  Natural  History,  Vol.  XXXIV,  pp.  243-56. 


96  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION  IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

tribes  of  East  Africa  that  are  organised  into  age-sets  a  man  is 
required  to  show  special  respect  to  all  men  of  his  father's  age- 
set  and  to  their  wives. 

The  social  function  of  this  is  obvious.  The  social  tradition  is 
handed  down  from  one  generation  to  the  next.  For  the  tradition 
to  be  maintained  it  must  have  authority  behind  it.  The  authority  is 
therefore  normally  recognised  as  possessed  by  members  of  the 
preceding  generation  and  it  is  they  who  exercise  discipline.  As  a 
result  of  this  the  relation  between  persons  of  the  two  generations 
usually  contains  an  element  of  inequality^  the  parents  and  those 
of  their  generation  being  in  a  position  of  superiority  over  the 
children  who  are  subordinate  to  them.  The  unequal  relation 
between  a  father  and  his  son  is  maintained  by  requiring  the  latter 
to  show  respect  to  the  former.  The  relation  is  asymmetrical. 

When  we  turn  to  the  relation  of  an  individual  to  his  grand- 
parents and  their  brothers  and  sisters  we  find  that  in  the  majority 
of  human  societies  relatives  of  the  second  ascending  generation 
are  treated  with  very  much  less  respect  than  those  of  the  first 
ascending  generation,  and  instead  of  a  marked  inequality  there  is  a 
tendency  to  approximate  to  a  friendly  equality. 

Considerations  of  space  forbid  any  full  discussion  of  this  feature 
of  social  structure,  which  is  one  of  very  great  importance.  There 
are  many  instances  in  which  the  grandparents  and  their  grand- 
children are  grouped  together  in  the  social  structure  in  opposition 
to  their  children  and  parents.  An  important  clue  to  the  under- 
standing of  the  subject  is  the  fact  that  in  the  flow  of  social  life 
through  time,  in  which  men  are  born,  become  mature  and  die, 
the  grandchildren  replace  their_grandparents.  S©   s/m/^^aj- 

In  many  societies  there  is  an  actual  joking  relationship,  usually 
of  a  relatively  mild  kind,  between  relatives  of  alternate  genera- 
tions. Grandchildren  make  fun  of  their  grandparents  and  of  those 
who  are  called  grandfather  and  grandmother  by  the  classificator}' 
system  of  terminology,  and  these  reply  in  kind. 

Grandparents  and  grandchildren  are  united  by  kinship;  they  are 
separated  by  age  and  by  the  social  difference  that  results  from  the 
fact  that  as  the  grandchildren  are  in  process  of  entering  into  full 
participation  in  the  social  life  of  the  community  the  grandparents 
are  gradually  retiring  from  it.  Important  duties  towards  his  re- 
latives in  his  own  and  even  more  in  his  parents'  generation  impose 
upon  an  individual  many  restraints;  but  with  those  of  the  second 


ON  JOKING  RELATIONSHIPS  97 

ascending  generation,  his  grandparents  and  collateral  relatives, 
there  can  be,  and  usually  is,  established  a  relationship  of  simple 
friendliness  relatively  free  from  restraint.  In  this  instance  also, 
it  is  suggested,  the  joking  relationship  is  a  method  of  ordering  a 
relation  which  combines  social  conjunction  and  disjunction. 

This  thesis  could,  I  believe,  be  strongly  supported  if  not 
demonstrated  by  considering  the  details  of  these  relationships. 
There  is  space  for  only  one  illustrative  point.  A  very  common 
form  of  joke  in  this  connection  is  for  the  grandchild  to  pretend 
that  he  wishes  to  marry  the  grandfather's  wife,  or  that  he  intends 
to  do  so  when  his  grandfather  dies,  or  to  treat  her  as  already  being 
his  wife.  Alternatively  the  grandfather  may  pretend  that  the  wife 
of  his  grandchild  is,  or  might  be,  his  wife,^  The  point  of  the  joke 
is  the  pretence  at  ignoring  the  difference  of  age  between  the 
grandparent  and  the  grandchild. 

In  various  parts  of  the  world  there  are  societies  in  which  a 
sister's  son  teases  and  otherwise  behaves  disrespectfully  towards 
his  mother's  brother.  In  these  instances  the  joking  relationship 
seems  generally  to  be  asymmetrical.  For  example  the  nephew- 
may  take  his  uncle's  property  but  not  vice  versa;  or,  as  amongst 
the  Nama  Hottentots,  the  nephew  may  take  a  fine  beast  from 
his  uncle's  herd  and  the  uncle  in  return  takes  a  wretched  beast 
from  that  of  the  nephew.  ^ 

The  kind  of  social  structure  in  which  this  custom  of  privileged 
disrespect  to  the  mother's  brother  occurs  in  its  most  marked  forms, 
for  example  the  Thonga  of  South-East  Africa,  Fiji  and  Tonga  in 
the  Pacific,  and  the  Central  Siouan  tribes  of  North  America,  is 
characterised  by  emphasis  on  patrilineal  lineage  and  a  marked 
distinction  between  relatives  through  the  father  and  relatives 
through  the  mother. 

In  a  former  publication^  I  offered  an  interpretation  of  this 
custom  of  privileged  familiarity  towards  the  mother's  brother. 
Briefly  it  is  as  follows.  For  the  continuance  of  a  social  system 
children  require  to  be  cared  for  and  to  be  trained.  Their  care 
demands    affectionate    and    unselfish    devotion;    their    training! 

^For  examples  see  Labouret,  Les  Tribus  du  Rameau  Lobi,  1931,  p.  248,  and 
Sarat  Chandra  Roy,  The  Oraons  of  Chota  Nagpur,  Ranchi,  1915.  PP-  352-4- 

^  A.  Winifred  Hoernl6,  'Social  Organisation  of  the  Nama  Hottentot'; 
American  Anthropologist,  N.s.,  Vol.  XXVII,  1925,  pp.  1-24. 

*  'The  Mother's  Brother  in  South  Africa',  South  African  Journal  of  Science, 
Vol.  XXI,  1924.     See  Chapter  I. 

4 


^ 


98  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

requires  that  they  shall  be  subjected  to  discipline.  In  the  societies 
with  which  we  are  concerned  there  is  something  of  a  division  of 
function  between  the  parents  and  other  relatives  on  the  two  sides, 
i  The  control  and  discipline  are  exercised  chiefly  by  the  father  and 
,'  his  brothers  and  generally  also  by  his  sisters;  these  are  relatives 
who  must  be  respected  and  obeyed.  It  is  the  mother  who  is 

'  primarily  responsible  for  the  affectionate  care;  the  mother  and  her 
brothers  and  sisters  are  therefore  relatives  who  can  be  looked  to 

I   for  assistance  and  indulgence.   The  mother's  brother  i^  called 

Ij-'male  mother'  in  Tonga  and  in  some  South  African  tribes. 

I  believe  that  this  interpretation  of  the  special  position  of  the 
mother's  brother  in  these  societies  has  been  confirmed  by  further 
field  work  since  I  wrote  the  article  referred  to.  But  I  was  quite 
aware  at  the  time  it  was  written  that  the  discussion  and  interpre- 
tation needed  to  be  supplemented  so  as  to  bring  them  into  line  with 
a  general  theory  of  the  social  functions  of  respect  and  disrespect. 

The  joking  relationship  with  the  mother's  brother  seems  to 
fit  well  with  the  general  theory  of  such  relationships  here  outlined. 
A  person's  most  important  duties  and  rights  attach  him  to  his 
paternal  relatives,  living  and  dead.  It  is  to  his  patrilineal  lineage 
or  clan  that  he  belongs.  For  the  members  of  his  mother's  lineage 
he  is  an  outsider,  though  one  in  whom  they  have  a  very  special 
and  tender  interest.  Thus  here  again  there  is  a  relation  in  which 
there  is  both  attachment,  or  conjunction,  and  separation,  or 
disjunction,  between  the  two  persons  concerned. 

But   let  us  remember  that  in  this  instance  the  relation  is 

,  asymmetrical.^  The  nephew  is  disrespectful  and  the  uncle 
accepts  the  disrespect.  There  is  inequality  and  the  nephew  is  the 

,  superior.  This  is  recognised  by  the  natives  themselves.  Thus  in 
Tonga  it  is  said  that  the  sister's  son  is  a  'chief  (eiki)  to  his  mother's 
brother,  and  Junod^  quotes  a  Thonga  native  as  saying  'The 
uterine  nephew  is  a  chief!  He  takes  any  liberty  he  likes  with  his 
maternal  uncle'.  Thus  the  joking  relationship  with  the  uncle 
does  not  merely  annul  the  usual  relation  between  the  two  genera- 
tions, it  reverses  it.  But  while  the  superiority  of  the  father  and  the 

^  There  are  some  societies  in  which  the  relation  between  a  mother's  brother 
and  a  sister's  son  is  approximately  symmetrical,  and  therefore  one  of  equality. 
This  seems  to  be  so  in  the  Western  Islands  of  Torres  Straits,  but  we  have  no 
information  as  to  any  teasing  or  joking,  though  it  is  said  that  each  of  the  two 
relatives  may  take  the  property  of  the  other. 

-  Life  of  a  South  African  Tribe,  Vol.  I,  p.  255. 


ON  JOKING   RELATIONSHIPS  99 

father's  sister  is  exhibited  in  the  respect  that  is  shown  to  them,  the 
nephew's  superiority  to  his  mother's  brother  takes  the  opposite 
form  of  permitted  disrespect. 

It  has  been  mentioned  that  there  is  a  widespread  tendency  to 
feel  that  a  man  should  show  respect  towards,  and  treat  as  social 
'  superiors,  his  relatives  in  the  generation  preceding  his  own,  and 
the  custom  of  joking  with,  and  at  the  expense  of,  the  maternal 
I  uncle  clearl)'  conflicts  with  this  tendency.  This  conflict  between 
principles  of  behaviour  helps  us  to  understand  what  seems  at  first 
sight  a  very  extraordinary  feature  of  the  kinship  terminology  of  the 
Thonga  tribe  and  the  VaNdau  tribe  in  South-East  Africa.  Amongst 
the  Thonga,  although  there  is  a  term  malutne  (=  male  mother)  for 
the  mother's  brother,  this  relative  is  also,  and  perhaps  more 
frequently,  referred  to  as  a  grandfather  (kokwana)  and  he  refers 
to  his  sister's  son  as  his  grandchild  {ntukulu).  In  the  VaNdau 
tribe  the  mother's  brother  and  also  the  mother's  brother's  son  are 
called  'grandfather'  {tetekidii,  literally  'great  father')  and  their 
wives  are  called  'grandmother'  (mbiya),  while  the  sister's  son  and 
the  father's  sister's  son  are  called  'grandchild'  (miizukulu). 

This  apparently  fantastic  w'ay  of  classifying  relatives  can  be 
interpreted  as  a  sort  of  legal  fiction  whereby  the  male  relatives 
of  the  mother's  lineage  are  grouped  together  as  all  standing  towards 
an  individual  in  the  same  general  relation.  Since  this  relation  is 
one  of  privileged  familiarity  on  the  one  side,  and  solicitude  and 
indulgence  on  the  other,  it  is  conceived  as  being  basically  the 
one  appropriate  for  a  grandchild  and  a  grandfather.  This  is 
indeed  in  the  majority  of  human  societies  the  relationship  in  W'hich 
this  pattern  of  behaviour  most  frequently  occurs.  By  thisjegal 
Jiction  the  mother's  brother  ceases  to  belong  to  the  first  ascending 
generation,  of  which  it  is  felt  that  the  members  ought  to  be 
respected. 

It  may  be  worth  while  to  justify  this  interpretation  by  con- 
sidering another  of  the  legal  fictions  of  the  VaNdau  terminology. 
In  all  these  south-eastern  Bantu  tribes  both  the  father's  sister. and 
the  sister,  particularly  the  elder  sister,  are  persons  who  must  be 
treated  with  great  respect.  They  are  also  both  of  them  members  of 
a  man's  own  patrilineal  lineage.  Amongst  the  VaNdau  the  father's 
sister  is  called  'female  father'  (tetadji)  and  so  also  is  the  sister.^ 

^  For  the  kinship  terminology  of  the  VaNdau  see  Boas,  'Das  Verwandtschafts- 
system  der  Vandau',  in  Zeitschrift  fiir  Etlmologie,  1922,  pp.  41-51. 


r 


100  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVK   SOCIETY 

Thus  by  the  fiction  of  terminological  classification  the  sister  is 
placed  in  the  father's  generation,  the  one  that  appropriately 
includes  persons  to  whom  one  must  exhibit  marked  respect. 

In  the  south-eastern  Bantu  tribes  there  is  assimilation  of  two 
kinds  of  joking  relatives,  the  grandfather  and  the  mother's  brother. 
It  may  help  our  understanding  of  this  to  consider  an  example 
in  which  the  grandfather  and  the  brother-in-law  are  similarly 
grouped  together.  The  Cherokee  Indians  of  North  America, 
probably  numbering  at  one  time  about  20,000,  were  divided  into 
seven  matrilineal  clans. ^  A  man  could  not  marry  a  woman  of  his 
own  clan  or  of  his  father's  clan.  Common  membership  of  the  same 
clan  connects  him  with  his  brothers  and  his  mother's  brothers. 
Towards  his  father  and  all  his  relatives  in  his  father's  clan  of  his 
own  or  his  father's  generation  he  is  required  by  custom  to  show  a 
marked  respect.  He  applies  the  kinship  term  for  'father'  not  only 
to  his  father's  brothers  but  also  to  the  sons  of  his  father's  sisters. 
Here  is  another  example  of  the  same  kind  of  fiction  as  described 
above;  the  relatives  of  his  own  generation  whom  he  is  required 
to  respect  and  who  belong  to  his  father's  matrilineal  lineage  are 
spoken  of  as  though  they  belonged  to  the  generation  of  his  parents. 
The  body  of  his  immediate  kindred  is  included  in  these  two 
clans,  that  of  his  mother  and  his  father.  To  the  other  clans  of  the 
tribe  he  is  in  a  sense  an  outsider.  But  with  two  of  them  he  is 
connected,  namely  with  the  clans  of  his  two  grandfathers,  his 
father's  father  and  his  mother's  father.  He  speaks  of  all  the 
members  of  these  two  clans,  of  whatever  age,  as  'grandfathers' 
and  'grandmothers'.  He  stands  in  a  joking  relationship  with  all 
of  them.  When  a  man  marries  he  must  respect  his  wife's  parents 
but  jokes  with  her  brothers  and  sisters. 

The  interesting  and  critical  feature  is  that  it  is  regarded  as 
particularly  appropriate  that  a  man  should  marry  a  woman  whom 
he  calls  'grandmother',  i.e.  a  member  of  his  father's  father's 
clan  or  his  mother's  father's  clan.  If  this  happens  his  v^  ife's  brothers 
and  sisters,  whom  he  continues  to  tease,  are  amongst  those  whom 
he  previously  teased  as  his  'grandfathers'  and  'grandmothers'. 
This  is  analogous  to  the  widely  spread  organisation  in  which  a 
man  has  a  joking  relationship  with  the  children  of  his  mother's 
brother  and  is  expected  to  marry  one  of  the  daughters. 

^  For  an  account  of  the  Cherokee  see  Gilbert,  in  Social  Anthropology  of 
North  American  Tribes,  pp.  285-338. 


ON  JOKING   RELATIONSHIPS  lOI 

It  ought  perhaps  to  be  mentioned  that  the  Cherokee  also  have 
a  one-sided  joking  relationship  in  which  a  man  teases  his  father's 
sister' S-husband.  The  same  custom  is  found  in  Mota  of  the  Bank 
Islands.  In  both  instances  we  have  a  society  organised  on  a 
matrilineal  basis  in  which  the  mother's  brother  is  respected,  the 
father's  sister's  son  is  called  'father'  (so  that  the  father's  sister's 
husband  is  the  father  of  a  'father'),  and  there  is  a  special  term 
for  the  father's  sister's  husband.  Further  observation  of  the 
societies  in  which  this  custom  occurs  is  required  before  we  can  be 
sure  of  its  interpretation.  I  do  not  remember  that  it  has  been 
reported  from  any  part  of  Africa. 

What  has  been  attempted  in  this  paper  is  to  define  in  the  most  ~) 
general  and  abstract  terms  the  kind  of  structural  situation  in  which  /     ; 
we  may  expect  to  find  well-marked  joking  relationships.  We  have- 
been  dealing  with  societies  in  which  the  basic  social  structure  is 
provided  by  kinship.  By  reason  of  his  birth  or  adoption  into  a 
certain  position  in  the  social  structure  an  individual  is  connected 
with  a  large  number  of  other  persons.  With  some  of  them  he 
finds  himself  in  a  definite  and  specific  jural  relation,  i.e.  one  which  (27 
can  be  defined  in  terms  of  rights  and  duties.  Who  these  persons 
will  be  and  what  will  be  the  rights  and  duties  depend  on  the  form 
taken  by  the  social  structure.  As  an  example  of  such  a  specific 
jural  relation  we  may  take  that  which  normally  exists  between 
a  father  and  son,  or  an  elder  brother  and  a  younger  brother. 
Relations  of  the  same  general  type  may  be  extended  over  a  con- 
siderable range  to  all  the  members  of  a  lineage  or  a  clan  or  an 
age-set.  Besides  these  specific  jural  relations  which  are  defined 
not  only  negatively  but  also  positively,  i.e.  in  terms  of  things  that 
must  be  done  as  well  as  things  that  must  not,  there  are  general  ^ 
jural  relations  which  are  expressed  almost  entirely  in  terms  of 
prohibitions  and  which  extend  throughout  the  whole  political 
society.  It  is  forbidden  to  kill  or  wound  other  persons  or  to  take  or 
destroy  their  property.  Besides  these  two  classes  of  social  relations\ 
there  is  another,  including  many  very  diverse  varieties,  which  can  I 
perhaps    be    called    relations    of   alliance    or   consociation.    For(  {J^ 
example,  there  is  a  form  of  alliance  of  very  great  importance  in  ' 
many  societies,  in  which  two  persons  or  two  groups  are  connected 
by  an  exchange  of  gifts  or  services.^.  Another  example  is  provided   J 

^  See  Mauss,  'Essai  sur  le  Don',  Annee  Sociologique,  Nouvelle  S6rie,  tome  I, 
pp.  30-186. 


102  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

by  the  institution  of  blood-brotherhood  which  is  so  widespread 
in  Africa. 

The  argument  of  this  paper  has  been  intended  to  show  that  the 
joking  relationship  is  one  special  form  of  alliance  in  this  sense.  An~ 
alliance  by  exchange  of  goods  and  services  may  be  associated  with 
a  joking  relationship,  as  in  the  instance  recorded  by  Professor 
Labouret.^  Or  it  may  be  combined  with  the  custom  of  avoidance. 
Thus  in  the  Andaman  Islands  the  parents  of  a  man  and  the  parents 
of  his  wife  avoid  all  contact  with  each  other  and  do  not  speak;  at 
the  same  time  it  is  the  custom  that  they  should  frequently  exchange 
presents  through  the  medium  of  the  younger  married  couple. 
But  the  exchange  of  gifts  may  also  exist  without  either  joking 
or  avoidance,  as  in  Samoa,  in  the  exchange  of  gifts  between 
the  family  of  a  man  and  the  family  of  the  woman  he  marries 
or  the  very  similar  exchange  between  a  chief  and  his  'talking 
chief. 

So  also  in  an  alliance  by  blood-brotherhood  there  may  be  a 
joking  relationship  as  amongst  the  Zande;^  and  in  the  somewhat 
similar  alliance  formed  by  exchange  of  names  there  may  also  be 
mutual  teasing.  But  in  alliances  of  this  kind  there  may  be  a 
relation  of  extreme  respect  and  even  of  avoidance.  Thus  in  the 
Yaralde  and  neighbouring  tribes  of  South  Australia  two  boys 
belonging  to  communities  distant  from  one  another,  and  therefore 
more  or  less  hostile,  are  brought  into  an  alliance  by  the  exchange  of 
their  respective  umbilical  cords.  The  relationship  thus  established 
is  a  sacred  one;  the  two  boys  may  never  speak  to  one  another. 
But  when  they  grow  up  they  enter  upon  a  regular  exchange  of 
gifts,  which  provides  the  machinery  for  a  sort  of  commerce 
between  the  two  groups  to  which  they  belong. 

Thus  the  four  modes  of  alliance  or  consociation,  (i)  through 
intermarriage,  (2)  by  exchange  of  goods  or  services,  (3)  by  blood- 
brotherhood  or  exchanges  of  names  or  sacra,  and  (4)  by  the  joking 
relationship,  may  exist  separately  or  combined  in  several  different 
ways.  The  comparative  study  of  these  combinations  presents 
a  number  of  interesting  but  complex  problems.  The  facts  recorded 
from  West  Africa  by  Professor  Labouret  and  Mademoiselle 
Paulme  afford  us  valuable  material.  But  a  good  deal  more  intensive 

^  Africa,  Vol.  II,  p.  245. 

^  Evans-Pritchard,  'Zande  Blood-brotherhood',  Africa,  Vol.  VI,  1933, 
pp.  369-401. 


ON  JOKING   RELATIONSHIPS  IO3 

field  research  is  needed  before  these  problems  of  social  structure 
can  be  satisfactorily  dealt  with. 

What  I  have  called  relations  by  alliance  need  to  be  compared 
with  true  contractual  relations.  The  latter  are  specific  jural 
relations  entered  into  by  two  persons  or  two  groups,  in  which 
either  party  has  definite  positive  obligations  towards  the  other, 
and  failure  to  carry  out  the  obligations  is  subject  to  a  legal 
sanction.  In  an  alliance  by  blood-brotherhood  there  are  general 
obligations  of  mutual  aid,  and  the  sanction  for  the  carrying  out 
of  these,  as  shown  by  Dr.  Evans- Pritchard,  is  of  a  kind  that  can 
be  called  magical  or  ritual.  In  the  alliance  by  exchange  of  gifts 
failure  to  fulfil  the  obligation  to  make  an  equivalent  return  for  a 
gift  received  breaks  the  alliance  and  substitutes  a  state  of  hostility 
and  may  also  cause  a  loss  of  prestige  for  the  defaulting  party. 
Professor  Mauss^  has  argued  that  in  this  kind  of  alliance  also 
there  is  a  magical  sanction,  but  it  is  very  doubtful  if  such  is 
always  present,  and  even  when  it  is  it  may  often  be  of  secondary 
importance. 

The  joking  relationship  is  in  some  ways  the  exact  opposite  of 
a  contractual  relation.  Instead  of  specific  duties  to  be  fulfilled  there  —1 
is  privileged  disrespect  and  freedom  or  even  licence,  and  the  only 
obligation  is  not  to  take  offence  at  the  disrespect  so  long  as  it  is 
kept  within  certain  bounds  defined  by  custom,  and  not  to  go  / 
beyond  those  bounds.  Any  default  in  the  relationship  is  like  ai 
breach  of  the  rules  of  etiquette;  the  person  concerned  is  regarded   i 
as  not  knowing  how  to  behave  himself. 

In  a  true  contractual  relationship  the  two  parties  are  conjoined 
by  a  definite  common  interest  in  reference  to  which  each  of  them 
accepts  specific  obligations.  It  makes  no  difference  that  in  other 
matters  their  interests  may  be  divergent.  In  the  joking  relation- 
ship and  in  some  avoidance  relationships,  such  as  that  between  a 
man  and  his  wife's  mother,  one  basic  determinant  is  that  the 
social  structure  separates  them  in  such  a  way  as  to  make  many  of 
their  interests  divergent,  so  that  conflict  or  hostility  might  result. 
The  alliance  by  extreme  respect,  by  partial  or  complete  avoidanceL  ^ 
prevents  such  conflict  but  keeps  the  parties  conjoined.  The  ^ 
alliance  by  joking  does  the  same  thing  in  a  different  way.  ' 

All  that  has  been,  or  could  be,  attempted  in  this  paper  is  to 
show  the  place  of  the  joking  relationship  in  a  general  comparative 

^  *Essai  sur  le  Don*. 


104  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

Study  of  social  structure.  What  I  have  called,  provisionally, 
relations  of  consociation  or  alliance  are  distinguished  from  the 
relations  set  up  by  common  membership  of  a  political  society 
which  are  defined  in  terms  of  general  obligations,  of  etiquette,  or 
morals,  or  of  law.  They  are  distinguished  also  from  true  con- 
tractual relations,  defined  by  some  specific  obligation  for  each 
contracting  party,  into  which  the  individual  enters  of  his  own 
volition.  They  are  further  to  be  distinguished  from  the  relations 
set  up  by  common  membership  of  a  domestic  group,  a  lineage  or  a 
clan,  each  of  which  has  to  be  defined  in  terms  of  a  whole  set  of 
socially  recognised  rights  and  duties^JRelations  of  consociation 
can  only  exist  between  individuals  or  groups  which  are  in  some 
way  socially  separated. 

This  paper  deals  only  with  formalised  or  standardised  Joking 
relations.  Teasing  or  making  fun  of  other  persons  is  of  course  a 
common  mode  of  behaviour  in  any  human  society.  It  tends  to 
occur  in  certain  kinds  of  social  situations.  Thus  I  have  observed 
in  certain  classes  in  English-speaking  countries  the  occurrence 
of  horse-play  between  young  men  and  women  as  a  preliminaiy  to 
courtship,  very  similar  to  the  way  in  which  a  Cherokee  Indian 
jokes  with  his  'grandmothers'.  Certainly  these  unformalised  modes 
of  behaviour  need  to  be  studied  by  the  sociologist.  For  the  purpose 
of  this  paper  it  is  sufficient  to  note  that  teasing  is  always^ a  coin- 
pound  of  friendliness  and  antagonism. 

The  scientific  explanation  of  the  institution  in  the  particular 

form  in  which  it  occurs  in  a  given  society  can  only  be  reached  by  an 

1    intensive  study  which  enables  us  to  see  it  as^  particular  example  of 

\   a  widespread  phenomenon  of  a  definite  class,  This  means  that  the 

whole  social  structure  has  to  be  thoroughly  examined  in  order  that 

the  particular  form  and  incidence  of  joking  relationships  can  be 

understood  as  part  of  a  consistent  system.  If  it  be  asked  why  that 

society  has  the  structure  that  it  does  have,  the  only  possible 

i  answer  w^ould  lie  in  its  history.  When  the  histor}^  is  unrecorded, 

I  as  it  is  for  the  native  societies  of  Africa,  we  can  only  indulge  in 

conjecture,  and  conjecture  gives  us  neither  scientific  nor  historical 

knowledge.^ 

^  The  general  theory  outlined  in  this  paper  is  one  that  I  have  presented  in 
lectures  at  various  universities  since  1909  as  part  of  the  general  study  of  the  forms 
of  social  structure.  In  arriving  at  the  present  formulation  of  it  I  have  been 
helped  by  discussions  with  Dr.  Meyer  Fortes. 


CHAPTER     V 

A   FURTHER  NOTE  ON  JOKING  RELATIONSHIPS^ 

PROFESSOR  Griaule's  article  on  'L' Alliance  cathartique'  in 
Africa  of  October  1948  raises  a  methodological  point  of 
considerable  importance.  If  we  wish  to  understand 
custom  or  institution  that  we  find  in  a  particular  society  there  ar^ 
two  ways  of  dealing  with  it.  One  is  to  examine  the  part  it  plays  (T) 
in  the,system  or  complex  of  customs  and  institutions  in  which  it_ 
is  found  and  the  meaning  that  it  has  within  this  complex  for  th£ 
peopIeThemselves./ Professor  Griaule  deals  in  this  way  with  the 
custom  by  which  the  Bozo  and  the  Dogon  exchange  insults  with 
each  other.  He  considers  it  as  an  element  in  a  complex  of  customs, 
institutions,  myths,  and  ideas  to  which  the  Dogon  themselves 
refer  by  the  term  wow^w/^  He  shows  us  also  what  meaning  the 
natives  themselves  attribute  to  this  exchange  of  insults  (p.  253). 
As  a  piece  of  analysis  the  article  is  admirable,  and  is  a  most  im- 
portant contribution  to  our  growing  knowledge  of  West  African 
society. 

But  there  is  another  method  open  to  us,  namely,  to  make  a 
wide  cornparative  study_of  all  those  types  of  social  relationship  (__^ 
in  which  two  persons  are  by  custom  permitted,  or  even  required, 
to  use  speech  or  behaviour  which  in  other  relationships  would  be 
grievously  offensive.  To  the  use  of  this  method  it  would  seem 
that  Professor  Griaule  objects.  Referring  to  what  has  already 
been  written  on  the  comparative  study  of  what  are  called  'joking 
relationships'  or  parentis  a.  plaisanterie  he  writes:  'Nous  adoptons^'V  _ 
vis-a-vis  travaux  parus  sur  cette  question,  une  attitude  negative.' J 

Ethnographers  had  reported  from  North. America,  Oceania, 
and_  Africa  instances  of  a  custom  by  which  persons  standing 
in  certain  relationships  resulting  either  from  kinship,  or  more 
usually  from  marriage,  were  permitted  or  required  to  behave 
towards  one  another  in  a  disrespectful  or  insulting  way  at  which 
no  offence  might  be  taken.  Such  relationships  came  to  be  called 
'joking  relationships',  admittedly  not  a  very  good  name.  The  most 


^  Reprinted  from  Africa,  Vol.  XIX,  1949,  pp.  133-140. 
105 


I06  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

numerous  and  widespread  examples  of  this  custom  were  in  the 
relationship  of  a  man  to  the  brothers  and  sisters  of  his  wife. 
But  it  was  also  found  in  some  instances  between  cross-cousins, 
between  mother's  brother  and  sister's  son,  and  in  a  somewhat 
milder  form  between  grandparents  and  grandchildren.  There 
thus  arose  a  problem  of  comparative  sociology:  What  is  there  in  all 
these  relationships  that  makes  this  type  of  behaviour  app reprice, 
meaningful,  and  functional? 

One  of  the  first  facts  that  strikes  the  sociological  enquirer  is 
that  the  custom  of  'joking'  with  the  wife's  brothers  and  sisters  is 
very  commonly  associated  with  a  custom  of  strict  avoidance  of  the 
wife's  mother,  frequently  of  the  wife's  father,  and  more  occasion- 
ally the  wife's  mother's  brother.  Since  it  is  clear  that  the  avoidance 
custom  and  the  joking  custom  are  direct  contraries,  or  polar^ 
opposites,  the  problem  immediately  became  one  of  dealing  with 
both  these  types  of  custom.  And  this  in  turn  made  it  necessary 
to  consider  certain  other  kinds  of  relationships. 

I  became  interested  in  this  whole  set  of  problems  in  1908  when 
I  was  trying  to  find  an  explanation  of  customs  of  avoidance  in  the 
Andaman  Islands.  There  the  parents  of  a  man  and  the  parents 
of  his  wife  must  avoid  each  other.  Their  relationship  is  described 
by  the  term  aka-yat,  from  a  stem  meaning  'forbidden'  and  a  prefix 
referring  to  the  mouth,  and,  therefore,  to  speech.  Persons  in  such 
a  relationship  might  not  speak  to  each  other.  On  the  other  hand 
I  was  told  that  they  will  regularly  send  each  other  presents.  The 
explanation  given  by  the  Andamanese  is:  'They  are  great  friends 
because  their  children  have  married.'  This  conception  of  avoid- 
ance relationships  as  relationships  of  friendship  I  have  found 
elsewhere.  Thus  in  Australia,  where  a  man  carefully  avoids  all 
social  contact  with  his  wife's  mother,  I  have  more  than  once 
been  told  that  she  is  the  greatest  friend  he  has  since  she  has  pro- 
vided him  with  a  wife.  Again,  the  joking  relationship  is  commonly 
referred  to  as  one  of  friendship.  'I  can  tease  my  mother's  brother 
and  take  his  property  because  we  are  great  friends;  I  am  the  son 
of  his  sister.'  'I  can  joke  with  my  grandfather  or  grandmother,  and 
they  will  joke  with  me  because  we  are  great  friends.' 

What  does  'friendship'  mean  in  these  contexts?  It  is  clearly 
something  different  from  the  relationship  of  solidarity  and  mutual 
help  between  two  brothers  or  a  father  and  son.  On  the  basis  of 
comparative  analysis  it  seems  to  me  that  the  assertion  of  'friend- 


A  FURTHER   NOTE   ON  JOKING   RELATIONSHIPS  I07 

ship'  means  an  obligation  for  the  two  persons  not  to  enter  into  1 
open  quarrel  or  conflict  with  each  other.  It  is  sufficiently  evident  1 
that  one  way  of  obviating  open  conflict  between  two  persons  is    }. 
for  them  to  avoid  one  another  or  treat  each  other  with  very  marked,^ 
respect.  I  think  it  is  also  fairly  evident  that  a  relationship  in  which!  ■ 
insults  are  exchanged  and  there  is  an  obligation  not  to  take  them  j 
seriously,  is  one  which,  by  means  of  sham  conflicts,  avoids  real/ 
ones.  ,.-^ 

This  theory  can  be  supported  by  reference  to  customs  of 
other  kinds,  of  which,  to  economise  space,  I  ^^  ill  only  mention  two 
that  are  typical  of  one  kind.  In  the  Andamans  I  was  told  that 
two  men  who  were  initiated  together  at  the  same  ceremony  of 
initiation  would  be  forbidden  thereafter  to  speak  to  one  another, 
but  would  regularly  exchange  gifts.  Again  the  explanation  was: 
'They  are  great  friends.'  In  South  Australia  there  was  a  custom 
whereby  two  boys,  born  about  the  same  time  in  two  clans  that 
were  normally  hostile,  were  united  into  a  special  relationship  by  the 
exchange  of  that  portion  of  the  umbilical  cord  which  remains 
on  the  infant  and  later  falls  off.  The  two  men  who  stand  in  this 
relationship  may  never  speak  to  each  other,  but  each  may  visit  in 
safety  the  clan  of  the  other  carrying  gifts  to  his  friend  and  receiving 
gifts  in  exchange.  Again  the  relationship  is  described  as  one  of  y 
great  friendship;  through  it  each  of  the  persons  is  safe  in  what  / 
would  otherwise  be  hostile  territory.  -^ 

A  careful  examination  of  a  great  many  instances  from  all  over? 
the  world  seems  to  me  to  justify  the  formulation  of  a  genexali- 
_theory.  But  these  special  forms  of  'friendship'  can,  of  course/ 
only  be  fully  dealt  with  in  terms  of  a  study  of  forms  of  social 
relationship  in  general,  and  this  is  not  the  place  in  which  to  take 
up  that  very  wide  subject.  Some  social  relationships  are  required 
by  custom  to  be  based  on  respect,  of  difl^crent  degrees  and  ex- 
pressed in  diff^erent  ways;  others  are  such  as  to  permit  a  certain 
degree  of  familiarity,  and  in  extreme  cases  of  licence.  The_rules 
of  etiquette  are  one  method  of  standardising  these  features  of 
social  relations.  The  respect  required  of  a  son  to  his  father  in  many 
African  tribes  must  be  exhibited  in  this  way.  The  avoidance 
relationship  is  in  one  sense  an  extreme  form  of  respect,  while  the 
joking  relationship  is  a  form  of  familiarity,  permitting  disrespectful 
behaviour,  and  in  extreme  instances,  licence.  It  is,  for  example,  a 
relationship  in  which,  in  some  cases,  obscenity  may  be  freely 


Io8  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

indulged  in,  as  between  the  Dogon  and  the  Bozo.  Obscene  talk,  in 
all  or  most  societies,  is  only  permissible  in  ordinary  social  inter- 
course between  persons  standing  in  a  specially  familiar  relationship. 
The  prohibition  against  any  reference  to  sexual  matters  before  a 
father,  and  still  more  before  a  father-in-law,  in  many  African 
societies,  exemplifies  this  contrast  between  respectful  and  familiar 
or  licentious  behaviour. 

The  theory,  of  which  I  gave  a  brief  outUne  in  an  earlier 
number  of  Africa^  and  to  which  M.  Griaule  adopts  a  negative 
attitude,  starts  from  the  position  that  the  customs  of  avoidance 
or  extreme  respect  towards  the  wife's  parents,  and  of  privileged 
'joking'  with  the  wife's  brothers  and  sisters,  can  be  regarded  as  the 
means  of  establishing  and  maintaining  social  equilibrium  in  a 
type  of  structural  situation  that  results  in  many  societies  from 
marriage.  In  this  situation  we  have  two  separate  and  distinct 
social  groups,  families  or  lineages,  which  are  brought  into  con- 
nection with  one  another  through  the  union  of  a  man  of  one  with 
a  woman  of  the  other.  The  husband  is  outside,  and  socially 
separated  from,  his  wife's  group.  Through  his  relationship  with 
her  he  is  in  an  indirect  or  mediated  relationship  with  individuals 
of  her  group.  What  is  required  for  social  equilibrium  is  that,  as 
far  as  possible,  he  should  not  enter  into  conflict  with  his  wife's 
group,  but  be  obliged  to  maintain  with  that  group  or  its  members 
a  'friendly'  relation.  Both  the  avoidance  customs  and  the  'joking' 
customs  are  the  means  by  which  this  situation  is  socially  regulated. 

Why  the  difference,  then,  between  the  behaviour  towards 
the  wife's  parents  and  that  towards  her  brothers  and  sisters? 
The  answer  lies  in  the  general  principle,  widely  recognised,  that 
towards  relatives  of  the  first  ascending  generation  respect  is 
required,  whereas  relations  of  familiarity  and  equality  are  ap- 
propriate between  persons  of  the  same  generation.  There  are, 
of  course,  examples  of  exceptions  to  this  rule,  such  as  joking 
relations  or  privileged  familiarity  tov/ards  the  father's  sister's 
husband  or  the  mother's  brother. 

Thus  the  special  structural  situation  considered  in  this  theory 
is  one  of  groups  which  maintain  their  separateness,  each  having 
its  own  system  of  internal  relationships  between  its  members,  and 
an  indirect  connection  of  a  person  of  one  group  with  the  other 

^  Africa,  Vol.  XIII,  No.  3,  1940,  pp.  195-210.     See  Chapter  IV. 


A   FURTHER   NOTE   ON  JOKING   RELATIONSHIPS  IO9 

group  through  a  particular  personal  relation.  In  the  instance  of 
marriage  the  indirect  relation  is  that  of  a  man  through  his  wife. 
The  custom  of  a  joking  relationship  with  the  mother's  brother  is    ^ 
found  in  societies  in  which  an  individual  belongs  to  a  patrilineal     f 
group,  and  therefore  has  an  indirect  relation  to  his  mother's     1 
group  through  his  mother.  The  widespread  custom  of  relationships    J 
of  familiarity  with  grandparents,  often  taking  the  form  of  a  joking 
relationship  (in  Australia,  Africa,  North  America,  the  Oraons  of 
India),  emphasises  the  relation  of  the  two  generations  as  being 
socially  separated.  The  grandparents  are  thus  placed  in  contrast 
with  the  relatives  of  the  parents'  generation,  and  the  relation  to 
one's  own  grandparent  is  an  indirect  one  through  a  parent.  The   J 
joking   relationship   between   cross-cousins   (Fiji,    Ojibwa,   etc.) 
is  frequently  a  relation  between  possible  relatives  by  marriage, 
but  the  relation  is  an  indirect  one  through  the  mother  or  through 
the  father's  sister. 

An  interesting  crucial  instance  for  the  theory  is  provided 
by  the  Crow  Indians,  who  have  matrilineal  clans.  A  man  must 
be  respectful  to  all  the  members  of  his  father's  clan;  though  he  is 
not  a  member  of  that  clan  his  relation  to  its  members  is  one  of 
close  solidarity.  In  the  other  clans  of  the  tribe  there  are  to  be  found 
some  men  who  are  sons  of  men  of  his  father's  clan.  They  belong 
to  clans  that  are  separate  and  distinct,  not  only  from  his  own  clan 
but  also  from  his  father's  clan.  With  such  men,  with  whom  his 
personal  relation  is  an  indirect  one  through  his  father's  clan, 
he  has  a  joking  relationship;  he  may  make  offensive  remarks  to 
them  or  receive  such  from  them  without  offence.  In  the  Crow 
tribe  this  relationship  has  been  developed  into  an  instrument  of 
social  control  of  conduct,  since  the  joking  relative  may  call  public 
attention  to  the  shortcomings  of  his  relative. 

The  Cherokee  also  had  a  system  of  matrilineal  clans,  and  a  man 
was  required  to  show  respect  to  all  the  members  of  his  father's  clan. 
But  with  the  clans  of  his  father's  father  and  his  mother's  father  he 
had  only  an  indirect  connection  through  a  parent.  He  called  all 
the  women  of  these  clans  'grandmother'  and  could  be  on  a 
relationship  of  familiarity  or  joking  with  them.  Since  marriage 
with  such  a  'grandmother'  was  approved  they  were  possible 
wives  or  sisters-in-law. 

The  theory  that  I  have  offered  of  joking  relationships  between 
persons  related  through  marriage  or  by  kinship  is  that  they  occur 


no  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

as  social  institutions  in  structural  situations  of  a  certain  general 
kind  in  which  there  are  two  groups,  the  separateness  of  which  is 
emphasised,  and  relations  are  established  indirectly  between  a 
person  in  one  group  and  the  members  or  some  of  the  members  of 
the  other.  The  relationship  may  be  said  to  be  one  which  expresses 
and  emphasises  both  detachment  (as  belonging  to  separated 
groups)  and  attachment  (through  the  indirect  personal  relation). 
These  relationships  of  'friendship',  by  avoidance  or  joking, 
contrast  in  a  marked  way  with  the  relationships  of  solidarity, 
involving  a  complex  system  of  obligations,  that  exist  within  a 
group  such  as  a  lineage  or  a  clan.  For  the  further  development 
of  the  theory  they  need  to  be  compared  also  with  those  relations 

-which  are  set  up,  between  persons  belonging  to  different  groups, 
by  the  regular  exchange  of  gifts.  Thus  the  theory  is  only  one  part 
of  an  attempt  to  deal  systematically  with  the  types  of  social 
relationship  that  are  to  be  found  in  primitive  societies. 

^  The  great  majority  of  instances  of  joking  relationships  that 
were  recorded  by  ethnographers  were  relationships  between 
individuals  connected  through  marriage  or  by  kinship.  Hence  the 
reference  to  them  in  French  as  relations  oiparenU.  But  there  were 
also  found  instances  of  a  similar  relation  between  groups  of  persons, 
by  which  a  member  of  one  group  was  permitted  and  expected  to 
offer  insulting  or  derogatory  remarks  to  any  member  of  the  other. 
A  good  example  is  provided  by  the  'coyote'  and  'wild  cat' 
moieties  of  Californian  tribes.  More  recently  similarcu  stoms 
have  been  reported  from  Africa  (Northern  Rhodesia,  Tanganyika, 
West  Africa)^  in  which  this  kind  of  relationship  exists  between  two 
clans  of  a  tribe  or  between  two  tribes.  These  obviously  present 
a  problem  of  a  somewhat  different  kind.  But  it  is  obvious  that 
any  valid  general  theory  of  joking  relationships  must  take  into 
account  these  relations  between  groups. 

Tribes  and  clans  are  distinct  separated  groups  each  maintaining 
its  own  identity  and  separateness.  Within  a  clan  the  relations  of 
its  members  are  those  of  solidarity  in  the  special  sense  in  which 
I  have  been  using  that  term  in  this  note.  Two  clans  may,  in  some 
instances,  be  united  in  a  way  in  which  there  is  a  permanent  union 
of  solidarity  between  the  clans  as  groups  and  the  members  thereof. 
On  the  other  hand  there  may  also  be  a  relation  between  two  clans 

^See  Bibliography,  p.  115. 


A   FURTHER  NOTE   ON  JOKING   RELATIONSHIPS  III 

of  active  or  latent  hostility.  There  is  a  third  possibility,  that 
between  two  particular  clans  there  may  be  a  relation  neither  of 
solidarity  nor  of  hostility  but  of  'friendship'  in  which  the  separate- 
ness  of  the  groups  is  emphasised,  but  open  conflict  between  the 
groups  or  the  members  on  the  two  sides  is  avoided  by  establishing 
a  relation  in  which  they  may  insult  each  other  without  giving 
or  taking  offence.  This  kind  of  thing  is  well  illustrated  in  the 
account  of  the  clans  of  the  Tallensi  given  by  Dr.  Meyer  Fortes.  ^ 
A  similar  relationship,  whereby  hostility  is  avoided,  may  exist 
between  two  tribes, as  in  the  instances  known  from  Tanganyika.- 
It  seems  to  me  that  in  this  way  the  joking  relationship  between 
clans  and  tribes  recorded  from  Africa  can  be  brought  within  the 
scope  of  a  single  theory  that  refers  all  instances  of  these  relation- 
ships to  a  certain  general  type  of  structural  situation.  It  should 
be  made  clear  that  what  such  a  theory  attempts  to  do  is  to  deal 
with  all  the  known  examples  of  a  certain  recognisable  type  of 
institutionalised  relationships  in  order  to  discover  what  common 
social  feature  makes  this  type  of  behaviour  appropriate,  meaning- 
ful, and  functional. 

It  is  evident  that  in  one  particular  respect  the  relation  between 
the  Dogon  and  the  Bozo  is  similar  to  the  relations  that  have  been 
described  from  other  parts  of  Africa,  namely,  in  the  exchange  of 
insults.  There  is  no  evidence  that  they  are  similar  in  other 
respects,  and  they  certainly  are  not  so  in  all.  The  relation  is 
spoken  of  as  an  'alliance',  but  it  is  something  very  diflferent  from 
an  alliance  between  two  nations  which  co-operate  in  fighting  a 
war  against  another.  The  term  'alliance'  is  therefore  not  entirely 
suitable,  nor  have  I  been  able  to  find  a  really  suitable  term.  I 
have  used  the  term  'friendship'  and  there  is  justification  for  this 
in  the  way  in  which  native  peoples  themselves  speak  of  friendship. 
In  Australian  tribes  a  man  may  have  a  'friend',, that  is,  a  person 
with  whom  he  has  a  special  personal  relationship.  In  one  region  a 
wife's  own  sister's  husband,  if  he  is  not  a  near  kinsman,  is  such  a 
friend.  In  other  regions  a  man  may  not  select  a  'friend'  from 
amongst  the  men  to  whom  he  applies  the  classificatory  term  for 
'brother'.  Between  'brothers'  relations  are  fixed  by  the  kinship 
system.    He   may  choose  a  man   who    stands   to   him   in   the 

^  Fortes,  M.,  The  Dynamics  of  Clanship  among  the  Tallensi,  London:  Oxford 
University  Press,  1945. 

^  See  Bibliography,  p.  115. 


[ 


112  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

classificatory  relation  of  'brother-in-law'  but  not  his  own  brother- 
in-law.  For  brothers-in-law  always  necessarily  belong  to  separated 
groups.  There  is  a  clear  distinction  made  between  friendship  and 
relationships  by  kinship. 

I  am  distinguishing,  therefore,  a  certain  class  of  what  I 
call  'friendship'  relations,  from  what  I  have  called  relations  of 
'solidarity'  established  by  kinship  or  by  membership  of  a  group 
such  as  a  lineage  or  clan.  These  terms  are  used  only  for  the  purpose  s 
of  the  present  analysis  because  in  this  matter,  as  in  so  many  others 
in  social  anthropology,  no  precise  technical  terms  are  yet  available. 

We  may  regard  as  one  type  of  'friendship'  in  this  sense  the 
relation  set  up  between  persons  or  groups  on  the  basis  of  a  con- 
tinued exchange  of  goods  and  services.  The  world-wide  custom  of 
gift-exchange  has  to  be  considered  in  this  connection.  But  there 
are  other  varieties;  one  group  may  bury  the  dead  of  the  other  or 
perform  other  ritual  services.  In  North-West  America  one  group 
would  call  in  a  'friend'  group  to  erect  a  totem-pole  for  them. 
A  component  of  the  relationship  between  groups  is  very  commonly 
a  certain  amount  and  kind  of  opposition,  meaning  by  that  term 
socially  controlled  and  regulated  antagonism.  The  two  groups 
may  regularly  engage  in  competitive  games  such  as  football.  In 
potlatch  in  North  America  there  is  competition  or  rivalry  in 
exchange  of  valuables.  Social  relations  of  friendly  rivalry  are  of 
considerable  theoretical  importance.  The  universities  of  Oxford 
and  Cambridge  maintain  a  certain  relation  by  competing  regu- 
larly in  rowing,  football,  etc.  The  joking  relationship  is  thus  one 
example  of  a  wider  kind;  for  it  is  a  relation  of  friendship  in  which 
there  is  an  appearance  of  antagonism,  controlled  by  conventional 
rules. 

The  'alliance'  between  the  Dogon  and  the  Bozo  described  and 
analysed  by  M.  Griaule  is  clearly  an  example  of  what  I  have  been 
referring  to  as  'friendship'.  The  Dogon  and  the  Bozo  are  separate 
peoples  distinguished  by  language  and  by  their  mode  of  life. 
The  prohibition  against  intermarriage  maintains  this  separation  by 
preventing  the  creation  of  relations  of  kinship  between  members 
of  the  two  groups.  The  'friendship'  appears  in  the  prohibition, 
under  supernatural  sanction,  against  the  shedding  of  the  blood 
of  a  member  of  the  allied  people,  and  in  the  regular  exchange 
of  gifts  and  services,  for  example,  the  services  that  individuals 
of  one  group  perform  in  the  ritual  purification  of  those  of  the 


A   FURTHER   NOTE   ON  JOKING   RELATIONSHIPS  II3 

Other,  To  these  is  added  a  'joking  relationship',  the  exchange  of 
insults  between  members  of  the  two  groups.  It  is  with  this  last 
feature  that  we  are  concerned  here. 

This  alliance  is  conceived  by  the  two  peoples  concerned  in 
terms  of  their  own  cosmological  system  of  myths  and  ideas,  and 
M.  Griaule's  article  is  an  important  addition  to  the  series  of 
publications  in  which  he  and  his  co-workers  have  given  the 
results  of  their  investigation  of  this  cosmology.  It  is  in  terms  of 
these  ideas  that  the  Dogon  interpret  the  exchange  of  insults.^ 
The  exchange  of  insults  is  'cathartic'  because  it  rids  the  livers  of 
both  parties  of  impurities.  M.  Griaule  has  thus  given  us  an  ex- 
planation of  the  exchange  of  insults  between  Dogon  and  Bozo  by 
showing  what  meaning  it  has  to  the  natives  themselves  and  also 
by  showing  its  interconnections  within  a  complex  system  of 
institutions,  ideas,  and  myths.  He  finds  that  the  most  important 
function  of  the  alliance  is  to  provide  what  he  calls,  for  lack  of  a 
more  suitable  term,  'purification'.  So,  provisionally,  he  proposes 
to  call  this  type  of  alliance,  as  found  in  an  extensive  region  of 
Africa,  'cathartic  alliance'.  Doubtless  he  would  not  suggest  that  we 
should  apply  this  name  to  the  exchange  of  insults  between  clans 
among  the  Tallensi  or  Bemba,  or  between  tribes  in  Tanganyika. 
M.  Marcel  Mauss  and  I  have  both  been  seeking  for  many 
years  to  find  a  satisfactory  general  theory  of  what  I  have  been 
calling  relations  of  'friendship'  between  separate  groups  of  per- 
sons belonging  to  separate  groups.  One  part  of  such  a  theory  must 
be  a  study  of  prestations  or  exchanges  of  goods  or  services. 
Another  must  be  a  study  of  'joking  relationships'.  It  is  towards 
such  studies  that  M.  Griaule  adopts,  as  he  says,  'a  negative 
attitude'.  He  suggests  that  to  classify  together  the  various  ex- 
amples of  'joking  relationships'  and  to  look  for  a  general  explana- 
tion, is  like  classifying  together  the  ceremonies  at  which  church 
bells  are  rung,  such  as  funerals  and  weddings,  calling  them  all 
ceremonies  a  cloches.  This  is  the  question  of  methodology  in  social 
anthropology  that  seems  to  me  so  important.  For  M.  Griaule 
seems  to  be  questioniiigLthe  scientific  validity  of  the  comparative 
method  as  a  means  of  arriving  at  general  theoretical  interpretations 
"of  social  institutions. 

It  is  only  by  the  use  of  a  comparative  method  that  we  can  arrive 

1  Africa,  Vol.  XVIII,  No.  4,  pp.  253-4- 


^114  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

at  general  explanations.  The  alternative  is  to  confine  ourselves 
to  particularistic  explanations  similar  to  those  of  the  historians. 
The  two  kinds  of  explanation  are  both  legitimate  and  do  not 
conflict;  but  both  are  needed  for  the  understanding  of  societies 
and  their  institutions.  That  the  Dogon  explain  the  exchange  of 
insults  as  a  means  of  purifying  the  liver  does  not  prevent  us  from 
treating  the  Dogon  institution  as  one  example  of  a  very  wide- 
spread form  of  'friendship'  in  which  such  exchange  is  a  distinctive 
feature. 

It  is  not  a  question  of  whether  my  theory,  or  any  other  general 
theory,  of  joking  relationships  is  or  is  not  satisfactory.  It  is  the 
different  question  of  whether  such  a  general  theory  is  possible, 
or  whether  attempts  to  arrive  at  one  should  be  abandoned  in 
favour  of  resting  content  with  particularistic  explanations. 

The  same  question  of  methodology  arises  in  connection  with 
the  conclusion  of  M.  Griaule's  article.  He  touches  briefly  on  the 
need  for  an  explanation  of  the  Dogon-Bozo  alliance  'en  tant  que 
systeme  de  groupes  couples  et  dont  les  deux  parties  ont  des 
prerogatives  et  devoirs  complementaires'.  He  finds  the  explanation 
in  'les  fondements  meme  de  la  metaphysique  dogon.  En  effet, 
des  I'origine  du  monde,  la  regie  etait  de  gemelleite.  Les  etres 
devaient  naitre  par  couple.'  This  is  therefore  a  particularistic 
explanation  in  terms  of  Dogon  ideas  about  twins. 

Relations  of  this  kind  between  paired  groups  are  to  be  found 
in  many  parts  of  the  world.  Outstanding  examples  are  provided 
by  the  moiety  organisations  of  North  and  South  America, 
Melanesia,  and  Australia.  The  most  usual  way  of  representing 
this  unity  in  duality,  linking  two  groups  into  one  society,  is  by 
pairs  of  opposites,  such  as  heaven  and  earth,  war  and  peace,  red 
and  white,  land  and  water,  coyote  and  wild  cat,  eaglehawk  and 
crow.  The  underlying  conception  is  therefore  that  of  the  union 
of  opposites,  as  in  the  philosophy  of  Heraclitus.  It  was  highly 
elaborated  by  the  Chinese  in  the  philosophy  of  Yin  and  Yang; 
yang  and  yin  are  male  and  female,  day  and  night,  summer  and 
winter,  activity  and  passivity,  etc.,  and  the  dictum  is  that  yang 
and  yin  together  are  required  to  make  a  unity  or  harmony  {tao) 
as  in  the  union  of  husband  and  wife,  or  the  union  of  winter  and 
summer  to  make  a  year. 

The  Dogon  are  therefore  unusual  when  they  represent  the 
relation  between  paired  groups  by  reference  to  human  twins. 


A   FURTHER   NOTE   ON  JOKING  RELATIONSHIPS  II5 

But  this  can  be  seen  to  be  only  a  special  development  of  a  con- 
ception that  is  very  widespread  in  Africa,  by  which  twins  are 
regarded  as  a  single  entity  divided  into  two  parts.  A  comparative 
study  of  African  customs  concerning  twins  shows  this  conception 
developed  in  a  number  of  different  ways. 

In  the  Dogon  cosmology  as  recorded  by  M.  Griaule  and  his 
associates  the  most  fundamental  conception  of  unity  in  duality 
seems  to  be  not  that  of  twin  births  but  rather  the  opposition  of 
the  masculine  and  feminine  principles,  just  as  in  the  yin  and  yang 
of  China.  Human  beings  are  born  endowed  with  both  principles 
and  it  is  by  operations  of  circumcision  and  clitoridectomy  that 
they  become  truly  male  and  female,  so  that  there  is  again  a 
Heraclitean  union  of  opposites  in  the  sexual  union  of  husband 
and  wife.  One  useful  clue  to  the  understanding  of  Dogon  cos- 
mological  ideas,  or  certain  of  them,  is  the  way  in  which  this 
duality  of  male  and  female  is  combined  with  the  duality  in  unity 
of  twins.  The  latter  form  of  duality  corresponds  to  the  number  2; 
the  former  to  the  opposition  between  3,  masculine  symbol,  and 
4,  feminine,  which  being  added  together  give  7,  the  symbol  of 
the  complete  being. 

The  symbolic  representations  of  the  Dogon  present  striking 
similarities  to  those  found  in  other  parts  of  the  world  besides 
West  Africa.  The  basis  of  any  scientific  understanding  of  them 
must  be  such  a  particularistic  study  as  is  being  made  by  M.  Griaule 
and  his  co-workers;  but  it  is  suggested  that  it  will  need  to  be 
supplemented  by  a  systematic  comparative  study  extended  as 
widely  as  possible.  The  conception  of  unity  in  duality  has  been 
used  by  man  not  only  in  the  establishment  of  systems  of  cosmology 
but  also  in  organising  social  structures.  A  comparative  study  of 
this,  as  of  joking  relationships,  may  be  expected  to  aid  in  most 
important  ways  the  understanding  of  the  Dogon  system  which, 
without  it,  would  seem  to  be  only  a  peculiar  product  of  a  particular 
people. 

BIBLIOGRAPHY 

Fortes,    M.    The   Dynaynics   of  Clanship   afuong   the    Talleiisi.    London 

Oxford  University  Press,  1945. 
Moreau,    R.    E.    'The    Joking    Relationship    (utani)    in    Tanganyika', 

Tanganyika  Notes  and  Records,  12,  1941,  pp.  i-io. 
—     'Joking  Relationships  in  Tanganyika',  Africa,  Vol.  XIV,  No.  3,  1944, 

pp.  386-400. 


Il6  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

Paulme,  Denise.  'Parent^  k  plaisanteries  et  alliance  par  le  sang  en  Afrique 

occidentale',  Africa,  Vol.  XII,  No.  4,  1939,  pp.  433-44. 
Pedler,  F.  J.  'Joking  Relationships  in  East  Africa',  Africa,  Vol.  XIII,  No. 

2,  1940,  pp.  170-3. 
Radcliffe-Brown,  A.   R.  'On  Joking  Relationships',   Africa,  Vol.   XII, 

No.  3,  1940,  pp.  195-210. 
Richards,  A.   I.  'Reciprocal  Clan  Relationships  among  the  Bemba  of 

N.  Rhodesia',  Man,  Vol.  XXXVII,  p.  222,  1927. 
Schapera,  I.  'Customs  relating  to  twins  in  South  Ahica\  yournal  Afr.  Soc, 

Vol.  XXVI,  cii,  pp.  117-37. 


CHAPTER    VI 

THE   SOCIOLOGICAL  THEORY  OF  TOTEMISM^ 

THERE  has  been  in  the  past  some  disagreement  and  discussion 
as  to  the  definition  of  totemism.  I  wish  to  avoid  as  far  as 
possible  entering  into  any  such  discussion.  The  purpose 
of  preUminary  definitions  in  science  is  to  mark  off  a  class  of 
phenomena  for  special  study.  A  term  is  useful  if  and  in  so  far  as 
it  brings  together  for  our  attention  a  number  of  phenomena  which 
are  in  reality,  and  not  merely  in  appearance,  closely  related  to 
one  another.  It  will  be  part  of  my  thesis  in  this  paper  that 
however  widely  or  narrowly  we  may  define  totemism,  we  cannot 
reach  an  understanding  of  the  phenomena  we  so  name  unless  we 
study  systematically  a  much  wider  group  of  phenomena,  namely, 
the  general  relation  between  man  and  natural  species  in  mytholog}' 
and  ritual.  It  may  well  be  asked  if  'totemism'  as  a  technical  term 
has  not  outlived  its  usefulness.  . .  - 

It  is  necessary,  however,  to  have  some  definition  to  guide  and 
control  our  discussion.  I  shall  use  the  term  in  the  wider  sense  to 
apply  wherever  a  society  is  divided  into  groups  and  there  is  a 
special  relation  between  each  group  and  one  or  more  classes  of 
objects  that  are  usually  natural  species  of  animals  or  plants  but 
may  occasionally  be  artificial  objects  or  parts  of  an  animal.  The 
word  is  sometimes  used  in  a  narrower  sense  and  applied  only 
when  the  groups  in  question  are  clans,  i.e.  exogamous  groups  of 
which  all  the  members  are  regarded  as  being  closely  related  by 
descent  in  one  line.  I  shall  regard  'clan  totemism'  as  only  one 

variety  of  totemism,  in  the  wider  sense. ^  

Even  in  the  narrower  sense  of  clan  totemism,  and  still  more 
in  the  wider  sense,  totemism  is  not  one  thing  but  is  a  general  name 

^  Reprinted  from  Proceedwgs  of  the  Fourth  Pacific  Science  Congress,  Ja^'a, 
1929. 

^  It  is  sometimes  said  that  totemism  has  two  aspects,  a  social  aspect  and  a 
religious  or  ritual  aspect.  What  is  referred  to  as  the  'social  aspect'  of  totemism 
is  simply  the  clan  organisation.  But  exogamous  clans  similar  in  all  essentials  to 
totemic  clans  so  far  as  economic  or  juridical  functions  go,  can,  as  we  well  know, 
exist  without  totemism.  The  so-called  'social  aspect'  of  clan  totemism  is  simply 
the  social  aspect  of  the  clan. 

117 


Il8  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

given  to  a  number  of  diverse  institutions  which  all  have,  or  seem 
to  have,  something  in  common.  Thus  even  in  the  Hmited  region 
of  Austraha,  which  has  a  single  homogeneous  culture  throughout, 
there  have  been  recorded  a  number  of  different  varieties  of 
totemism,  and  new  varieties  are  being  discovered  by  systematic 
researches  now  in  progress. 

In  the  south-east  of  the  continent  is  found  sex-totemism,  i.e. 
an  association  of  the  two  sex-groups,  men  and  women,  with  two 
animal  species.  In  the  coastal  districts  of  New  South  Wales,  for 
example,  the  bat  is  the  totem  or  animal  representative  of  the  men 
and  the  tree-creeper  {Climacteris  sp.)  is  that  of  the  women. 

In  many  parts  of  Australia  the  tribe  is  divided  into  two 
exogamous  moieties,  patrilineal  in  some  regions,  matrilineal  in 
others.  In  some  instances  thte  moieties  are  named  after  species  of 
animals,  generally  birds.  Amongst  such  names  are  the  following 
pairs:  crow  and  white  cockatoo,  white  cockatoo  and  black  cockatoo, 
eaglehawk  and  crow,  native  companion  and  turkey,  hill  kangaroo 
and  long-legged  kangaroo.  In  other  instances  the  meanings  of  the 
moiety  names  have  not  been  discovered,  and  in  some  of  them,  at 
any  rate,  it  seems  certain  that  they  are  not  animal  names. 

In  many  of  the  tribes  that  have  this  dual  division,  indepen- 
dently of  whether  the  moieties  are  named  after  animals  or  not, 
there  is  a  classification  of  animals  and  frequently  of  other  natural 
objects  whereby  some  are  regarded  as  belonging  to  one  moiety 
and  others  to  the  other. 

Such  moiety  totemism,  if  we  may  use  that  term  for  any  such 
association  between  the  moiety  and  one  or  more  natural  species, 
is  found  in  a  number  of  different  varieties  in  Australia,  and  still 
other  varieties  are  found  in  Melanesia  and  in  North  America. 

Over  a  large  part  of  Australia  the  tribe  is  divided  into  four 
groups  which  have  often  been  called  'classes'  but  which  I  prefer 
to  call  'sections'.  The  easiest  way  to  understand  this  division 
into  four  is  to  regard  it  as  constituted  by  the  intersection  of  a  pair 
of  patrilineal  moieties  and  a  pair  of  matrilineal  moieties.^ 

^  If  we  denote  the  four  sections  as  A,  B,  C,  and  D,  the  matrilineal  moieties 
are  A  +  C  and  B  +  D;  the  patrilineal  moieties  are  A  +  D  and  B  +  C.  Since 
a  man  may  not  marry  within  his  o^-n  patrilineal  moiety  or  within  his  own 
matrilineal  moiety  it  will  follow  that  a  man  of  A  can  only  marry  a  woman  of  B 
and  their  children  must  belong  to  section  D,  i.e.  to  the  patrilineal  moiety  of  the 
father  (A)  and  to  the  matrilineal  moiety  of  the  mother  (B). 


THE  SOCIOLOGICAL  THEORY   OF   TOTEMISM  II9 

These  sections  are  not  as  a  rule  named  after  species  of  animals, 
though  there  are  one  or  two  instances  in  which  a  section  name  is 
also  the  name  of  an  animal.  Thus  Bandjur  in  Yukumbil  is  the 
name  of  a  section  and  also  of  the  native  bear.  In  some  tribes, 
however,  there  is  a  definite  association  between  each  section  and 
one  or  more  species  of  animal.  Thus  in  the  Nigena  tribe  of  the 
Kimberley  district  of  Western  Australia  the  four  sections  are 
associated  with  four  species  of  hawk.  In  some  regions  this  associa- 
tion does  not  carry  with  it  any  prohibition  against  killing  or  eating 
the  animal  associated  with  one's  own  or  any  other  section.  In 
part  of  Queensland,  however,  each  section  has  associated  with  it  a 
number  of  species  of  animals  and  there  is  a  rule  that  the  members 
of  a  section  may  not  eat  the  animals  so  associated  with  their 
section. 

This  'section  totemism'  requires  further  investigation.  We 
may  distinguish,  however,  three  varieties.  In  one  each  section  has 
associated  with  it  a  single  species  of  animal  which  is  representative 
of  the  section  in  somewhat  the  same  way  as  the  sex-totem  is  the 
representative  of  the  sex-group.  In  a  second  variety  each  section 
stands  in  a  special  ritual  relation  to  a  certain  limited  number  of 
species  which  may  not  be  eaten  by  the  members  of  the  section. 
In  the  third  variety  a  great  number  of  species  of  animals  are  classi- 
fied as  belonging  to  one  or  other  of  the  four  sections  but  there  is  no 
rule  against  eating  the  animals  belonging  to  one's  own  section. 
The  one  thing  that  is  common  to  these  varieties  is  that  each 
section  is  differentiated  from  the  others  and  given  its  own  in- 
dividuality by  being  associated  with  one  or  more  animal  species. 

In  some  tribes  the  four  sections  are  again  subdivided  each  into 
two  parts,  giving  a  division  of  the  tribe  into  eight  sub-sections. 
In  some  of  these  tribes  there  exist  special  associations  between 
the  sub-sections  and  certain  natural  species.  Further  investigation 
is  needed  before  we  can  profitably  discuss  this  subject. 

If  now  we  turn  to  clan-totemism  we  find  a  number  of  different 
varieties  of  this  in  Australia,  too  many,  in  fact,  to  be  even  enu- 
merated in  a  short  paper.  Matrilineal  clan  totemism  of  different 
varieties  occurs  in  three,  or  possibly  four,  separate  areas  in  the 
east,  north,  and  west  of  the  continent.  In  Melville  and  Bathurst 
Islands  there  are  three  matrilineal  phratries  subdivided  into 
twenty-two  clans.  Each  clan  is  associated  with  one  natural  species, 
usually  a  species  of  animal  or  plant,  though  one  or  two  clans  have  . 


I20  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

two  totems  and  one  has  three.  The  association  between  the  clan 
and  its  totem  is  aipparently  of  very  Httle  importance  in  the  Hfe 
of  the  tribe.  There  is  no  prohibition  against  eating  or  using  the 
totem,  there  are  no  totemic  ceremonies,  and  totemism  has  httle 
influence  on  the  mythology. 

The  matrilincal  clan  totemism  of  some  tribes  of  New  South 
Wales,  Victoria  and  South  Australia  seems  to  be  of  somewhat 
more  importance.  Here  we  find  matrilineal  moieties  sometimes 
named  totemically,  sometimes  not,  and  each  moiety  is  divided  into 
a  number  of  clans.  Each  clan  has  one  or  more  natural  species 
regarded  as  belonging  to  it.  Where  there  are  several  species 
associated  with  each  clan,  as  is  the  case  in  many  tribes,  one  of 
them  is  regarded  as  more  important  than  the  others  and  the  clan 
is  named  after  it.  Throughout  this  region  there  is,  so  far  as  we 
know,  no  prohibition  against  killing  or  eating  the  totem. 

Totemic  ceremonial  is  apparently  little  developed  nor  have  we 
any  evidence  of  any  elaborate  totemic  mythology  connected  with 
matrilineal  totemism. 

It  should  be  noted  that  throughout  Australia  the  most  im- 
portant group  for  social  purposes  is  the  horde,  i.e.  a  small  group 
occupying  and  ow^ning  a  certain  defined  territory,  and  that  the 
horde  is  normally  strictly  patrilineal.  It  follows  that  wherever 
there  is  a  system  of  matrilineal  totemic  clans  the  clan  consists  of 
individuals  scattered  through  a  number  of  hordes.  We  thus  get  a 
double  grouping  of  individuals.  For  most  social  purposes  the 
individual  is  dependent  on  the  local  group,  i.e.  the  horde,  to  which 
he  is  connected  through  his  father,  while  at  the  same  time  he  is 
also  connected  through  his  mother  to  a  totemic  group  the  members 
of  which  are  scattered  throughout  the  tribe. 

Patrilineal  totemism  in  Australia  is  more  difficult  to  describe 
briefly  than  is  matrilineal  totemism.  Where  it  exists  the  primary 
totemic  group  is  usually  the  horde,  i.e.  the  small  patrilineal  local 
group.  In  some  regions  the  horde  is  a  clan,  i.e.  it  consists  of  close 
relatives  in  the  male  line  and  is  therefore  exogamous.  But  in  a 
few  regions  the  horde  is  not  a  clan  in  this  sense. 

As  an  example  of  one  variety  of  patrilineal  totemism  we  may 
take  the  tribes  at  the  mouth  of  the  Murray  River  (Yaralde,  etc.). 
Here  each  horde  is  a  local  clan  and  each  clan  has  one  or  more 
species  of  natural  object  associated  w  ith  it.  There  is  no  prohibition 
against  eating  the  totem  of  one's  clan,  but  it  is  regarded  with  some 


THE   SOCIOLOGICAL   THEORY   OF   TOTEMISM  121 

respect.  There  is  no  evidence  of  totemic  ceremonial  or  of  any 
elaborate  totemic  mythology.  The  function  of  the  totem  seems  to 
be  merely  to  act  as  the  representative  of  the  group. 

Perhaps  the  most  important,  and  certainly  the  most  interesting, 
form  of  totemism  in  Australia  is  that  to  a  brief  consideration  of 
which  we  now  pass.  This  consists  of  a  fourfold  association  between 
(i)  the  horde,  i.e.  the  patrilineal  local  group,  (2)  a  certain  number 
of  classes  of  objects,  animals,  plants,  and  other  things  such  as  rain, 
sun  and  hot  weather,  cold  weather,  babies,  etc.,  (3)  certain  sacred 
spots  within  the  territory  of  the  horde,  frequently  water-holes, 
each  one  of  which  is  specially  associated  with  one  or  more  of  the 
'totems'  of  the  group,  and  (4)  certain  mythical  beings  who  are 
supposed  to  have  given  rise  to  these  sacred  spots  in  the  mythical 
period  of  the  beginning  of  the  world.  This  system  of  totemism 
is  now  being  traced  and  studied  in  a  number  of  variant  forms  over 
a  very  large  part  of  the  Australian  continent.  It  \^"as  formerly 
known  best  from  the  centre  of  the  continent,  where,  however,  the 
Aranda  have  it  in  a  somewhat  modified  or  anomalous  form. 
We  now  know  that  it  exists  or  existed  over  a  large  part  of  Western 
Australia.  Recently  it  has  been  discovered  and  studied  in  the 
Cape  York  Peninsula  by  Miss  McConnel.  At  the  beginning  of  this 
year  I  was  able  to  demonstrate  its  former  existence  on  the  east 
coast  of  Australia  in  the  north  of  New  South  Wales  and  in  southern 
Queensland. 

Where  this  type  of  totemism  is  found  it  is  usually  accompanied 
by  a  system  of  ceremonies  for  the  increase  of  natural  species.  The 
members  of  the  horde,  or  some  of  them,  proceed  to  the  totem 
centre  or  sacred  spot  connected  with  a  natural  species  and  perform 
there  a  ceremony  which  is  believed  to  result  in  an  increase  of 
that  species.  There  is  also  an  elaborate  mythology  dealing  with  the 
sacred  totem  centres  and  with  the  mythical  beings  who  gave  rise 
to  them. 

It  may  be  noted  that  this  kind  of  totemism  may  coexist  in 
the  same  tribe  with  other  kinds.  Thus  in  the  Dieri  tribe  it  exists 
together  with  a  system  of  matrilineal  clan  totemism.  In  some 
parts  it  coexists  v.ith  section  totemism. 

Finally,  we  may  note  that  in  some  parts  of  Australia  there 
exists  what  is  sometimes  called  individual  or  personal  totemism. 
This  is  a  special  relation  between  an  individual  and  some  one  or 
more  species  of  animal.  A  good  example  is  found  in  some  tribes 


122  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

of  New  South  Wales  where  every  medicine-man  has  one  or  more 
of  such  personal  totems.  It  is  through  his  association  with  the 
animal  species  that  he  acquires  his  power  to  perform  magic. 
Whether  we  call  this  totemism  or  not,  it  is  quite  evident  that  it  is 
closely  related  to  totemism  and  that  any  theory  of  totemism,  to  be 
satisfactory,  must  take  it  into  account. 

This  brief  and  very  incomplete  survey  of  Australian  institutions 
has  shown  us  that  special  associations  of  groups  or  individuals 
with  natural  species  exist  in  that  region  in  a  number  of  different 
forms.  We  find  all  gradations  from  a  tribe  with  no  form  of  totemism 
at  all  (such  as  the  Bad  of  northern  Dampier  Land)  through  tribes 
such  as  the  Melville  Islanders  where  totemism  of  a  simple  form 
exists  but  is  of  comparatively  little  importance  in  the  life  of  the 
tribe,  to  a  tribe  such  as  the  Dieri  which  combines  in  a  complex 
system  two  forms  of  totemism,  one  of  matrilineal  clans  and  the 
other  of  patrilineal  hordes,  with  a  highly  elaborated  totemic 
ritual  and  mythology.  The  only  thing  that  these  totemic  systems 
have  in  common  is  the  general  tendency  to  characterise  the  seg- 
ments into  which  society  is  divided  by  an  association  between 
each  segment  and  some  natural  species  or  some  portion  of  nature. 
The  association  may  take  any  one  of  a  number  of  different  forms. 

In  the  past  the  theoretical  discussion  of  totemism  was  almost 
entirely  concerned  with  speculations  as  to  its  possible  origin. 
If  we  use  the  word  origin  to  mean  the  historical  process  by  which 
an  institution  or  custom  or  a  state  of  culture  comes  into  existence, 
then  it  is  clear  that  the  very  diverse  forms  of  totemism  that  exist 
all  over  the  world  must  have  had  very  diverse  origins.  To  be 
able  to  speak  of  an  origin  of  totemism  we  must  assume  that  all 
these  diverse  institutions  that  we  include  under  the  one  general 
term  have  been  derived  by  successive  modifications  from  a  single 
form.  There  does  not  seem  to  me  to  be  a  particle  of  evidence  to 
justify  such  an  assumption.  But  even  if  we  make  it  we  can  still 
only  speculate  as  to  what  this  original  form  of  totemism  may  have 
been,  as  to  the  enormously  complex  series  of  events  which  could 
have  produced  from  it  the  various  existing  totemic  systems,  and 
as  to  where,  when,  and  how  that  hypothetical  original  form  of 
totemism  came  into  existence.  And  such  speculations,  being  for 
ever  incapable  of  inductive  verification,  can  be  nothing  more 
than  speculations  and  can  have  no  value  for  a  science  of  culture. 

For  sociology,  or  social  anthropology,  by  which  I  understand 


I: 


THE   SOCIOLOGICAL   THEORY   OF   TOTEMISM  123 

the  Study  of  the  phenomena  of  culture  by  the  same  inductive 
methods  that  are  in  use  in  the  natural  sciences,  the  phenomena  of 
totemism  present  a  problem  of  a  different  kind.  The  task  of  the 
inductive  sciences  is  to  discover  the  universal  or  the  general  in  the 
particular.  That  of  a  science  of  culture  is  to  reduce  the  complex 
data  with  which  it  deals  to  a  limited  number  of  general  laws  or 
principles.  Approaching  totemism  in  this  way  we  may  formulate 
the  problem  that  it  presents  in  the  form  of  the  question,  'Can  we 
show  that  totemism  is  a  special  form  of  a  phenomenon  which  is 
universal  in  human  society  and  is  therefore  present  in  different 
forms  in  all  cultures?' 

The  most  important  attempt  to  arrive  at  a  sociological  theory 
of  totemism  is  that  of  the  late  Professor  Durkheim  in  his  work 
Les  Formes  elementaires  de  la  Vie  religieuse.  I  think  that  that  work 
is  an  important  and  permanent  contribution  to  sociological  theory, 
but  that  it  does  not  provide  a  complete  and  satisfactory  theory 
of  totemism.  I  shall  attempt  to  point  out,  in  the  briefest  possible 
way,  where  Durkheim's  theor)^  seems  to  me  to  fail. 

Durkheim  speaks  of  the  totem  as  being  'sacred'  to  the  members 
of  the  group  of  which  it  is  the  totem.  This  is  to  use  the  term 
'sacred'  in  a  sense  somewhat  different  from  that  which  it  has  at  the 
present  day  in  English  or  even  in  French,  and  not  even  identical 
with,  though  somewhat  nearer  to,  the  meaning  that  sacer  had  in 
Latin.  I  prefer  to  use  a  term  which  is  as  free  as  possible  from 
special  connotations,  and  therefore  instead  of  saying  that  the 
totem  is  sacred  I  find  it  preferable  to  say  that  there  is  a  'ritual 
relation'  between  persons  and  their  totem.  There  exists  a  ritual 
relation  whenever  a  society  imposes  on  its  members  a  certain 
attitude  towards  an  object,  which  attitude  involves  some  measure 
of  respect  expressed  in  a  traditional  mode  of  behaviour  with 
reference  to  that  object.  Thus  the  relation  between  a  Christian 
and  the  first  day  of  the  week  is  a  typical  example  of  a  ritual 
relation. 

Every  society  adopts,  and  imposes  upon  its  members,  to\\ards 
certain  objects,  this  attitude  of  mind  and  behaviour  which  I  am 
calling  the  ritual  attitude.  There  are,  not  only  in  different  societies, 
but  in  the  same  society  in  different  references,  many  different 
varieties  of  this  attitude,  but  all  the  varieties  have  something  in 
common.  Moreover  the  ritual  attitude  may  vary  from  a  very 
indefinite  one  to  a  definite  and  highly  organised  one. 


124  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

One  of  the  important  problems  of  sociology  is  therefore  to 
discover  the  function  of  this  universal  element  of  culture  and 
to  formulate  its  laws.  This  general  problem  obviously  includes  a 
vast  number  of  partial  problems  of  which  the  problem  of  totemism 
is  one.  That  problem  may  be  stated  as  being  that  of  discovering 
why  in  certain  societies  a  ritual  attitude  towards  a  certain  species 
of  natural  object  is  imposed  upon  the  members  of  a  particular 
social  group.  It  is  obvious  that  no  solution  of  the  lesser  problem 
of  totemism  can  be  satisfactory  unless  it  conforms  with  or  is  part 
of  a  general  solution  of  the  wider  problem,  i.e.  a  theory  of  ritual 
relations  in  general. 

With  regard  to  the  general  problem  Durkheim's  theory  is  that 
the  primary  object  of  the  ritual  attitude  is  the  social  order  itself, 
and  that  any  thing  becomes  an  object  of  that  attitude  when  it 
stands  in  a  certain  relation  to  the  social  order.  This  general 
theory,  with  which  I  agree,  obviously  amounts  to  very  little  until 
we  have  succeeded  in  defining  the  more  important  types  of 
relation  to  the  social  order  which  result  in  the  object  which  stands 
in  such  a  relation  becoming  an  object  of  ritual  attitude. 

If  I  may  restate  in  my  own  terms  Durkheim's  theory  of  totem- 
ism it  is  as  follows.  A  social  group  such  as  a  clan  can  only  possess 
solidarity  and  permanence  if  it  is  'the  object  of  sentiments  of 
attachment  in  the  minds  of  its  members.  For  such  sentiments 
to  be  maintained  in  existence  they  must  be  given  occasional 
collective  expression.  By  a  law  that  can  be,  I  think,  readily 
verified,  all  regular  collective  expressions  of  social  sentiments 
tend  to  take  on  a  ritual  form.  And  in  ritual,  again  by  a  necessary 
law,  some  more  or  less  concrete  object  is  required  which  can  act 
as  the  representative  of  the  group.  So  that  it  is  a  normal  procedure 
that  the  sentiment  of  attachment  to  a  group  shall  be  expressed 
in  some  formalised  collective  behaviour  having  reference  to  an 
object  that  represents  the  group  itself. 

A  typical  example  is  to  be  found  in  our  own  society.  National 
solidarity  depends  on  a  sentiment  of  patriotism  in  the  minds  of  the 
nation.  This  sentiment,  in  conformity  with  the  laws  stated  above, 
tends  to  find  some  of  its  chief  expressions  in  reference  to  such 
concrete  objects  as  flags,  or  kings  and  presidents,  and  such  objects 
become  in  this  way  objects  of  the  ritual  attitude. 

Part  of  a  king's  sacredness,  whether  in  Africa  or  in  Europe, 
is  due  to  the  fact  that  he  is  the  representative  of  the  national 


THE   SOCIOLOGICAL   THEORY   OF   TOTEMISM  1 25 

solidarity  and  unity,  and  the  ritual  that  surrounds  him  is  the 
means  by  which  patriotic  sentiments  are  maintained.  In  the  same 
way  in  the  flag  we  have  an  object  which  is  'sacred'  because  it  is 
the  concrete  material  representative  or  emblem  of  a  social  group 
and  its  solidarity. 

Durkheim  compares  the  totem  of  a  clan  with  the  flag  of  a 
nation.  The  comparison  is  valid,  in  a  very  general  sense,  for  some 
forms  of  totemism,  if  not  for  all.  But  putting  the  comparison  aside, 
the  theory  is  that  the  totem  is  'sacred'  as  Durkheim  says,  or  is  an 
object  of  ritual  attitude,  as  I  prefer  to  say,  because  it  is  the  concrete 
representative  or  emblem  of  a  social  group.  And  the  function  of 
the  ritual  attitude  towards  the  totem  is  to  express  and  so  to  main- 
tain in  existence  the  solidarity  of  the  social  group. 

With  Durkheim's  theory  as  stated  above  in  my  own  terms  I 
am  in  agreement,  but  I  do  not  regard  it  as  complete.  In  the  first 
place  it  seems  to  me  that  totemism  has  other  functions  besides  the 
one  indicated  above.  Secondly,  the  theory  so  far  as  stated  above 
does  not  explain  why  so  many  peoples  in  America,  Asia,  Africa  and 
Australasia  should  select  as  emblems  or  representatives  of  clans 
or  other  social  groups  species  of  animals  or  plants.  It  is  true  that 
Durkheim  off"ers  an  answer  to  this  question,  but  it  is  an  entirely 
unsatisfactory  one.  He  regards  as  an  essential  part  of  totemism  the 
use  of  totemic  emblems  or  designs,  i.e.  figured  representations 
of  the  totemic  animal  or  plant,  and  suggests  that  the  reason  for 
selecting  natural  objects  as  emblems  of  social  groups  is  because 
they  are  capable  of  being  used  in  this  way. 

This  hypothesis  fails  as  soon  as  we  apply  it  to  the  facts.  In 
Australia  no  designs  are  made  of  the  sex  totems  or  of  the  totems  of 
the  moieties  or  sections,  and  even  for  clan  totemism  there  are  many 
tribes  that  do  not  make  any  representations  of  their  totems. 
Totemic  designs,  which  for  Durkheim  are  so  important  or  indeed 
so  essential  a  part  of  totemism,  are  characteristic  of  central  and 
northern  Australia  but  not  of  the  continent  as  a  whole. 

Moreover,  the  reason  suggested  for  the  selection  of  natural 
objects  as  emblems  of  social  groups  is  of  too  accidental  a  character 
to  give  a  satisfying  explanation  of  an  institution  that  is  so  wide- 
spread as  totemism.  There  must  surely  be  some  much  more  im- 
portant reason  why  all  these  peoples  all  over  the  world  find  it 
appropriate  to  represent  social  groups  in  this  way  by  associating 
each  one  with  some  animal  or  plant. 


126  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

This,  then,  is  where  I  think  Durklicim's  theory'  of  totemism 
fails.  It  implies  that  the  totem  owes  its  sacred  or  ritual  character 
solely  to  its  position  as  the  emblem  of  a  group.  Now  there  are  a 
number  of  peoples  who  have  no  form  of  totemism  amongst  whom 
we  still  find  that  natural  species  such  as  animals  and  plants  are 
objects  of  ritual  or  of  the  ritual  attitude  expressed  in  mythology. 
And  even  amongst  totemic  peoples  such  as  the  Australian  tribes 
the  ritual  customs  relating  to  natural  species  are  not  all  totemic. 
In  other  words  the  phenomena  which  we  have  agreed  to  denote 
by  the  term  totemism  are  merely  a  part  of  a  much  larger  class  of 
phenomena  which  includes  all  sorts  of  ritual  relations  between 
man  and  natural  species.  No  theory  of  totemism  is  satisfactory 
unless  it  conforms  with  a  more  general  theory  providing  an 
explanation  of  many  other  things  besides  totemism.  Durkheim's 
theory  fails  to  do  this. 

In  a  great  number,  and  I  believe  probably  in  all,  of  the  societies 
where  man  depends  entirely  or  largely  on  the  hunting  of  wild 
animals  and  the  collection  of  wild  plants,  whether  they  have  any 
form  of  totemism  or  not,  the  animals  and  plants  are  made  objects 
of  the  ritual  attitude.  This  is  done  frequently,  though  perhaps  not 
quite  universally,  in  mythology,  in  which  animal  species  are 
personified  and  regarded  as  ancestors  or  culture  heroes.  It  is  done 
also  by  a  mass  of  customs  relating  to  animals  and  plants.  This 
system  of  ritual  and  mythological  relations  between  man  and 
natural  species  can  be  best  studied  in  non-totemic  peoples  such 
as  the  Eskimo  or  the  Andaman  Islanders.  In  such  societies  we 
find  that  the  relation  between  the  society  and  the  natural  species 
is  a  general  one,  all  the  most  important  animals  and  plants  being 
treated  as  in  some  way  sacred  (either  in  ritual  or  in  mythology) 
and  some  being  regarded  as  more  sacred  than  others,  but  any 
single  species  being  equally  sacred  to  every  member  of  the  whole 
community.  The  ritual  attitude  of  the  Andaman  Islanders  towards 
the  turtle,  of  Californian  Indians  to  the  salmon,  of  the  peoples  of 
North  America  and  northern  Asia  to  the  bear,  constitutes  a 
relation  between  the  whole  society  and  the  sacred  species. 

Now  totemism,  I  would  suggest,  arises  from  or  is  a  special 
development  of  this  general  ritual  relation  between  man  and 
natural  species.  Let  us  assume  for  the  moment  that  such  a  general 
ritual  relation  of  man  to  nature  is  universal  in  hunting  societies, 
as  I  believe  it  can  be  shown  to  be.  When  the  society  becomes 


THE  SOCIOLOGICAL   THEORY   OF   TOTEMISM  1 27 

differentiated  into  segmentary  groups  such  as  clans,  a  process  of 
ritual  specialisation  takes  place  by  which  each  segment  acquires  a 
special  and  particular  relation  to  some  one  or  more  of  the  sacra 
of  the  community,  i.e.  to  some  one  or  more  natural  species. 
The  totem  of  the  clan  or  group  is  still  sacred  in  some  sense  to 
the  whole  community,  but  is  now  specially  sacred,  and  in  some 
special  way,  to  the  segment  of  which  it  is  the  totem. 

The  process  here  suggested  as  the  active  principle  in  the 
development  of  totemism  is  one  which  I  believe  to  be  of  great 
importance  in  social  development,  and  which  can  be  observed  in 
other  phenomena.  Thus,  to  take  only  one  example,  and  perhaps 
not  the  best,  in  the  Roman  Church  the  saints  are  sacred  to  all 
members  of  the  church  as  a  whole.  But  the  church  is  segmented 
into  local  congregations  and  a  congregation  is  often  placed  in  a 
special  relation  to  one  particular  saint  to  whom  its  chapel  is 
dedicated.  This  is,  I  think,  parallel  to  clan  or  group  totemism. 
We  might  also  draw  a  significant  though  not  quite  exact  analogy 
between  the  patron  saint  of  an  individual  and  the  personal  totem 
or  guardian  animal  of  Australian  and  American  tribes. 

There  is  no  space  in  this  paper  to  discuss  this  process  of 
ritual  specialisation,  and  indeed  any  adequate  treatment  of  the 
subject  would  require  us  to  deal  with  the  vvhole  process  of  social 
differentiation  and  segmentation.  I  will  refer  to  a  single  example 
that  may  help  to  illustrate  the  problem.  Amongst  the  Eskimo  of 
part  of  North  America  one  of  the  most  important  features  of  their 
adaptation  to  their  environment  is  the  sharp  division  between 
winter  and  summer,  and  between  the  winter  animals  and  the 
summer  animals.  There  is  a  complex  system  of  ritual  relations 
between  the  society  and  all  the  most  important  of  these  animals 
and  in  this  ritual  the  opposition  between  summer  and  winter 
is  strongly  expressed.  Thus  you  may  not  eat  reindeer  meat 
,  (summer  food)  and  walrus  meat  (winter  food)  on  the  same  day. 
The  Eskimo  have  made  for  themselves  a  segmentation  into  two 
groups,  one  consisting  of  all  the  persons  born  in  the  summer  and 
the  other  of  those  born  in  the  \\intcr,  and  there  is  some  slight 
ritual  specialisation,  the  summer  people  being  regarded  as  specially 
connected  with  the  summer  animals  and  the  winter  people  with  the 
winter  animals.  This  is  not  quite  totemism,  but  it  is  clearly  related 
to  it,  and  illustrates,  I  think,  the  process  by  which  totemism  arises. 

In  this  way,  I  think,  we  can  formulate  a  sociological  theory 


120  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

of  totemism  which  incorporates  a  great  deal  of  Durkheim's 
analysis  and  is  not  open  to  the  criticisms  that  can  be  levelled 
against  Durkheim's  own  presentation.  We  start  with  the  em- 
pirical generalisation  that  amongst  hunting  and  collecting  peoples 
the  more  important  animals  and  plants  and  natural  phenomena 
are  treated,  in  custom  and  in  myth,  as  being  'sacred',  i.e.  they 
are  made,  in  various  ways  and  in  different  degrees,  objects  of  the 
ritual  attitude.  Primarily  this  ritual  relation  between  man  and 
nature  is  a  general  one  between  the  society  as  a  whole  and  its 
sacra.  When  the  society  is  differentiated,  i.e.  divided  into  seg- 
ments or  social  groups  marked  off  from  one  another  and  each 
having  its  own  solidarity  and  individuality,  there  comes  into  action 
a  principle  which  is  more  widespread  than  totemism  and  is 
indeed  an  important  part  of  the  general  process  of  social  differ- 
entiation, a  principle  by  which  within  the  general  relation  of  the 
society  to  its  sacra  there  are  established  special  relations  between 
each  group  or  segment  and  some  one  or  more  of  those  sacra. 

This  theory  incorporates  what  I  think  is  the  most  valuable 
part  of  Durkheim's  analysis,  in  the  recognition  that  the  function  of 
the  ritual  relation  of  the  group  to  its  totem  is  to  express  and  so  to 
maintain  in  existence  the  solidarity  of  the  group.  It  gives  moreover 
a  reason,  which  can  be  shown,  I  think,  to  be  grounded  in  the 
very  nature  of  social  organisation  itself,  for  the  selection  of  natural 
species  as  emblems  or  representatives  of  social  groups. 

Before  leaving  this  part  of  the  discussion  I  would  like  to  touch 
on  one  further  point.  Durkheim,  in  reference  to  clan  totemism, 
emphasises  the  clan  and  its  solidarity.  The  totem,  for  him,  is 
primarily  the  means  by  which  the  clan  recognises  and  expresses 
its  unity.  But  the  matter  is  much  more  complex  than  this.  The 
clan  is  merely  a  segment  of  a  larger  society  which  also  has  its 
solidarity.  By  its  special  relation  to  its  totem  or  totems  the  clan 
recognises  its  unity  and  its  individuality.  This  is  simply  a  special 
example  of  the  universal  process  by  which  solidarity  is  created 
and  maintained  by  uniting  a  number  of  individuals  in  a  collective 
relation  to  the  same  sacred  object  or  objects.  By  the  fact  that  each 
clan  has  its  own  totem  there  is  expressed  the  differentiation  and 
opposition  between  clan  and  clan.  The  kangaroo  men  not  only 
recognise  the  bond  that  unites  them  as  kangaroo  men  but  also 
recognise  their  difference  from  the  emu  men  and  the  bandicoot 
men  and  so  on.  But  also  the  wider  unity  and  solidarity  of  the 


THE   SOCIOLOGICAL   THEORY   OF   TOTEMISM  1 29 

whole  totemic  society  is  expressed  by  the  fact  that  the  society  as  a 
whole,  through  its  segments,  stands  in  a  ritual  relation  to  nature 
as  a  whole.  This  is  seen  very  well  in  the  system  of  increase 
ceremonies  that  is  so  widespread  in  Australia.  Each  group  is 
responsible  for  the  ritual  care  of  a  certain  number  of  species  by 
which  the  maintenance  of  that  species  is  believed  to  be  assured. 
For  the  tribe  all  these  species  are  of  importance,  and  the  ceremonies 
are  thus  a  sort  of  co-operative  effort,  involving  a  division  of 
(ritual)  labour,  by  which  the  normal  processes  of  nature  and  the 
supply  of  food  are  provided  for.  One  of  the  results  of  Durkheim's 
theory  is  that  it  over-emphasises  the  clan  and  clan  solidarity. 
Totemism  does  more  than  express  the  unity  of  the  clan;  it  also 
expresses  the  unity  of  totemic  society  as  a  whole  in  the  relations 
of  the  clans  to  one  another  within  that  wider  unity. 

The  result  of  my  argument,  if  it  is  valid,  is  to  substitute  for 
the  problem  of  totemism  another  problem.  The  question  that  now 
demands  an  answer  is,  'Why  do  the  majority  of  what  are  called 
primitive  peoples  adopt  in  their  custom  and  myth  a  ritual  attitude 
towards  animals  and  other  natural  species?'  My  aim  in  this  paper 
has  simply  been  to  exhibit  as  exactly  as  possible  in  a  brief  space 
the  relation  of  the  problem  of  totemism  to  this  wider  problem. 

It  is  obvious  that  I  cannot  attempt  in  a  mere  conclusion  to  a 
paper  to  deal  with  this  subject  of  the  relation  in  myth  and  ritual 
of  man  and  nature.  I  attempted  some  years  ago  to  deal  with  it  in 
reference  to  the  customs  and  beliefs  of  one  non-totemic  people,  the 
Andaman  Islanders.  As  a  result  of  that  and  other  investigations  I 
was  led  to  formulate  the  following  law:  Any  object  or  event  which 
has  important  effects  upon  the  well-being  (material  or  spiritual) 
of  a  society,  or  any  thing  which  stands  for  or  represents  any  such 
object  or  event,  tends  to  become  an  object  of  the  ritual  attitude. 

I  have  given  reasons  for  rejecting  Durkheim's  theory  that  in 
totemism  natural  species  become  sacred  because  they  are  selected 
as  representatives  of  social  groups,  and  I  hold,  on  the  contrar}', 
that  natural  species  are  selected  as  representatives  of  social 
groups,  such  as  clans,  because  they  are  already  objects  of  the 
ritual  attitude  on  quite  another  basis,  by  virtue  of  the  general 
law  of  the  ritual  expression  of  social  values  stated  above. 

In  modern  thought  we  are  accustomed  to  draw  a  distinction 
between  the  social  order  and  the  natural  order.  We  regard  society 
as  consisting  of  certain  human  beings  grouped  in  a  social  structure 
5 


130  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION  IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

under  certain  moral  principles  or  laws,  and  we  place  over  against 
the  society  its  environment,  consisting  of  geographical  features, 
flora  and  fauna,  climate  with  its  seasonal  changes,  and  so  on, 
governed  by  natural  law. 

For  certain  purposes  this  contrast  of  society  and  environment, 
of  man  and  nature,  is  a  useful  one,  but  we  must  not  let  it  mislead 
us.  From  another  and  very  important  point  of  view  the  natural 
order  enters  into  and  becomes  part  of  the  social  order.  The 
seasonal  changes  that  control  the  rhythm  of  social  life,  the  animals 
and  plants  that  are  used  for  food  or  other  purposes,  these  enter 
into  and  become  an  essential  part  of  the  social  life,  the  social  order. 
I  believe  that  it  can  be  shown  that  it  is  just  in  so  far  as  they  thus 
enter  into  the  social  order  that  natural  phenomena  and  natural 
objects  become,  either  in  themselves,  or  through  things  or  beings 
that  represent  them,  objects  of  the  ritual  attitude,  and  I  have 
already  tried  to  demonstrate  this  so  far  as  the  Andaman  Islanders 
are  concerned.  Our  own  explicit  conception  of  a  natural  order 
and  of  natural  law  does  not  exist  amongst  the  more  primitive 
peoples,  though  the  germs  out  of  which  it  develops  do  exist  in  the 
empirical  control  of  causal  processes  in  technical  activities.  For 
primitive  man  the  universe  as  a  whole  is  a  moral  or  social  order 
governed  not  by  what  we  call  natural  law  but  rather  by  what 
we  must  call  moral  or  ritual  law.  The  recognition  of  this  concep- 
tion, implicit  but  not  explicit,  in  ritual  and  in  myth  is,  I  believe, 
one  of  the  most  important  steps  towards  the  proper  understanding 
not  only  of  what  is  sometimes  called  'primitive  mentality'  but 
also  of  all  the  phenomena  that  w^e  group  vaguely  around  the 
term  religion.^ 

A  study  of  primitive  myth  and  ritual  from  this  point  of  view 
is,  I  think,  very  illuminating.  In  Australia,  for  example,  there  are 
innumerable  ways  in  which  the  natives  have  built  up  between 
themselves  and  the  phenomena  of  nature  a  system  of  relations 
which  are  essentially  similar  to  the  relations  that  they  have  built 
up  in  their  social  structure  between  one  human  being  and  another. 

^  A  more  precise  way  of  stating  the  view  I  am  here  suggesting  is  that  in  every 
human  society  there  inevitably  exist  two  different  and  in  a  certain  sense  con- 
flicting conceptions  of  nature.  One  of  them,  the  naturalistic,  is  implicit  every- 
where in  technology,  and  in  our  twentieth  century  European  culture,  with  its 
great  development  of  control  over  natural  phenomena,  has  become  explicit  and 
preponderant  in  our  thought.  The  other,  which  might  be  called  the  mythological 
or  spiritualistic  conception,  is  implicit  in  myth  and  in  religion,  and  often 
becomes  explicit  in  philosophy. 


THE   SOCIOLOGICAL   THEORY   OF  TOTEMISM  131 

I  can  do  no  more  than  mention  examples.  One  is  the  personi- 
fication of  natural  phenomena  and  of  natural  species.  A  species  of 
animal  is  personified,  i.e.  treated  for  certain  purposes  as  if  it  were 
a  human  being,  and  in  the  mythology  such  personified  species 
are  regarded  as  ancestors  or  culture  heroes.  The  function  of  this 
process  of  personification  is  that  it  permits  nature  to  be  thought 
of  as  if  it  were  a  society  of  persons,  and  so  makes  of  it  a  social  or 
moral  order.  Another  of  the  processes  by  which,  in  Australia,  the 
world  of  nature  is  brought  within  the  social  order  is  to  be  found 
in  the  systems  of  classification  of  natural  species,  existing  in  a 
number  of  diverse  forms  in  different  parts  of  the  continent  with 
this  one  thing  in  common  to  them  all,  that  the  more  important 
natural  species  are  so  classified  that  each  one  is  regarded  as 
belonging  to  a  certain  social  group,  and  occupying  a  specific 
position  in  the  social  structure. 

Although  there  is  always  a  danger  in  short  formulas  I  think. 
it  does  not  misrepresent  Australian  totemism  to  describe  it  as  a 
mechanism  by  which  a  system  of  social  solidarities  is  established 
between  man  and  nature.  The  mechanism  has  been  worked  out  in 
many  different  ways,  and  much  more  elaborately  in  some  than  in 
others,  but  everywhere  it  possesses  this  character. 

The  suggestion  I  put  forward,  therefore,  is  that  totemism  is 
part  of  a  larger  whole,  and  that  one  important  w^ay  in  which  we  can 
characterise  this  whole  is  that  it  provides  a  representation  of  the 
universe  as  a  moral  or  social  order.  Durkheim,  if  he  did  not  actually 
formulate  this  view,  at  any  rate  came  near  to  it.  But  his  conception 
seems  to  have  been  that  the  process  by  which  this  takes  place 
is  by  a  projection  of  society  into  external  nature.  On  the  contrary, 
I  hold  that  the  process  is  one  by  which,  in  the  fashioning  of 
culture,  external  nature,  so  called,  comes  to  be  incorporated  in 
the  social  order  as  an  essential  part  of  it. 

Now  the  conception  of  the  universe  as  a  moral  order  is  not 
confined  to  primitive  peoples,  but  is  an  essential  part  of  every 
system  of  religion.  It  is,  I  think,  a  universal  element  in  human 
culture.  With  the  question  of  why  this  should  be  so  I  cannot  now 
attempt  to  deal. 

I  may  summarise  what  I  have  tried  to  say  as  follows:  A 
sociological  theory  of  totemism  must  be  able  to  show  that  totemism 
is  simply  a  special  form  taken  in  certain  definite  conditions  by  an 
element  or  process  of  culture  that  is  universal  and  necessary. 


n 


132  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

Durkheim's  attempt  to  provide  such  a  theory  fails  in  certaii 
important  respects.  We  can,  however,  incorporate  a  good  dea 
of  Durkheim's  analysis  in  a  theory  which  rests  on  the  sam( 
general  hypothesis  of  the  nature  and  function  of  ritual  or  th< 
'sacred'. 

Finally,  my  argument  has  brought  out  something  of  the  con 
ditions  in  which  this  universal  element  of  culture  is  most  likeb 
to  take  the  form  of  totemism.  These  are  (i)  dependence  wholh 
or  in  part  on  natural  productions  for  subsistence,  and  (2)  th( 
existence  of  a  segmentary  organisation  into  clans  and  moieties  o: 
other  similar  social  units.  The  Andamanese  and  the  Eskimo  hav< 
(i)  but  not  (2),  and  they  have  no  totemism  though  they  have  th( 
material  out  of  which  totemism  could  easily  be  made.  There  are 
of  course,  apparent  exceptions  to  this  generalisation,  in  som< 
of  the  tribes  of  Africa,  America  and  Melanesia.  The  detailec 
examination  of  these,  which  of  course  cannot  be  undertaken  in  i 
brief  paper,  really  serves,  I  believe,  to  confirm  the  rule. 

I  would  not  be  understood  to  maintain  the  view  that  totemism 
or  rather  the  diflferent  institutions  which  in  different  parts  of  th< 
world  we  call  by  this  general  term,  have  arisen  independently  o 
one  another.  I  think  that  it  is  very  likely.  But  it  does  not  matter  fo: 
the  sociologist,  at  any  rate  in  the  present  state  of  our  knowledge 
If  anyone  wishes  to  believe  that  all  the  existing  forms  of  totemisn: 
have  come  into  existence  by  a  process  of  what  is  rather  unsatisfac- 
torily called  'diffusion'  from  a  single  centre,  I  have  no  objection 
I  would  point  out  that  totemism  has  not  spread  everywhere,  oi 
evenly,  and  that  it  has  not  survived  equally  in  all  regions.  It  is 
sufficient  for  my  argument  if  we  can  say  that  it  is  only  where  ^sr 
certain  other  features  of  culture  are  present  that  totemism  is 
likely  to  be  accepted  by  a  people  when  it  is  brought  to  them  from 
outside,  or  is  likely  to  remain  in  active  existence  after  it  has 
been  introduced. 


the] 
asfi 
one 
ITiii 


lek 

i 


ie 


CHAPTER     VII 

TABOO  1 

THE  purpose  of  this  lecture,  which  you  have  done  me  the 
honour  of  inviting  me  to  deHver,  is  to  commemorate 
the  work  of  Sir  James  Frazer,  as  an  example  of  life-long 
Qfbingle-minded  devotion  to  scientific  investigation  and  as  having 
vepontributed,  in  as  large  a  measure  as  that  of  any  man,  to  laying 
(ifthe  foundations  of  the  science  of  social  anthropology.  It  therefore 
eieems  to  me  appropriate  to  select  as  the  subject  of  my  discourse 
pne  which  Sir  James  was  the  first  to  investigate  systematically 
(lalf  a  century  ago,  when  he  wrote  the  article  on  'Taboo'  for  the 
ijiinth  edition  of  the  Encyclopaedia  Britannica,  and  to  the  elucida- 
;ion  of  which  he  has  made  many  successive  contributions  in  his 
vritings  since  that  time. 

The  English  word  'taboo'  is  derived  from  the  Polynesian 
vord  'tabu'  (with  the  accent  on  the  first  syllable).  In  the  languages 
)f  Polynesia  the  word  means  simply  'to  forbid',  'forbidden',  and 
:an  be  applied  to  any  sort  of  prohibition.  A  rule  of  etiquette,  an 
)rder  issued  by  a  chief,  an  injunction  to  children  not  to  meddle 
vith  the  possessions  of  their  elders,  may  all  be  expressed  by  the 
ise  of  the  word  tabu. 

The  early  voyagers  in  Polynesia  adopted  the  word  to  refer  to 
prohibitions  of  a  special  kind,  which  may  be  illustrated  by  an 
xample.  Certain  things  such  as  a  newly-born  infant,  a  corpse  or 
he  personof  a  chief  are  said  to  be  tabu.  This  means  that  one  should, 
Jis  far  as  possible,  avoid  touching  them.  A  man  who  does  touch 
3i)ne  of  these  tabu  objects  immediately  becomes  tabu  himself. 
This  means  two  things.  In  the  first  place  a  man  who  is  tabu 
n  this  sense  must  observe  a  number  of  special  restrictions  on  his 
jehaviour;  for  example,  he  may  not  use  his  hands  to  feed  himself, 
^e  is  regarded  as  being  in  a  state  of  danger,  and  this  is  generally 
tated  by  saying  that  if  he  fails  to  observe  the  customary  pre- 
:autions  he  will  be  ill  and  perhaps  die.  In  the  second  place  he  is 
Iso  dangerous  to  other  persons — he  is  tabu  in  the  same  sense 
s  the  thing  he  has  touched.  If  he  should  come  in  contact  with 

^  The  Frazer  Lecture,  1939. 
133 


134  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY  ] 

Utensils  in  which,  or  the  fire  at  which,  food  is  cooked,  the  dangerous 
influence  would  be  communicated  to  the  food  and  so  injure 
anyone  who  partook  of  it.  A  person  who  is  tabu  in  this  way,  as 
by  touching  a  corpse,  can  be  restored  to  his  normal  condition 
by  rites  of  purification  or  desacralisation.  He  is  then  said  to  be 
Jioa  again,  this  term  being  the  contrary  of  tabu. 

Sir  James  Frazer  has  told  us  that  when  he  took  up  the  study 
of  taboo  in  1886  the  current  view  of  anthropologists  at  the  time 
was  that  the  institution  in  question  was  confined  to  the  brown  and 
black  races  of  the  Pacific,  but  that  as  a  result  of  his  investigations 
he  came  to  the  conclusion  that  the  Polynesian  body  of  practices 
and  beliefs  *is  only  one  of  a  number  of  similar  systems  of  super- 
stition which  among  many,  perhaps  all  the  races  of  men  have 
contributed  in  large  measure,  under  many  different  names  and 
with  many  variations  of  detail,  to  build  up  the  complex  fabric 
of  society  in  all  the  various  sides  or  elements  of  it  which  we 
describe  as  religious,  social,  political,  moral  and  economic'. 

The  use  of  the  word  taboo  in  anthropology  for  customs  all 
over  the  world  which  resemble  in  essentials  the  example  given 
from  Polynesia  seems  to  me  undesirable  and  inconvenient.' 
There  is  the  fact  already  mentioned  that  in  the  Polynesian 
language  the  word  tabu  has  a  much  wider  meaning,  equivalent, 
to  our  own  word  'forbidden'.  This  has  produced  a  good  deal  of, 
confusion  in  the  literature  relating  to  Polynesia  owing  to  the 
ambiguity  resulting  from  two  different  uses  of  the  same  word.' 
You  will  have  noticed  that  I  have  used  the  word  taboo  (with  the 
English  spelling  and  pronunciation)  in  the  meaning  that  it  has  fori 
anthropologists,  and  tabu  (with  the  Polynesian  spelling  and, 
pronunciation)  in  special  reference  to  Polynesia  and  in  the  Poly- 
nesian sense.  But  this  is  not  entirely  satisfactory. 

I  propose  to  refer  to  the  customs  we  are  considering  as  'ritual 
avoidances'  or  'ritual  prohibitions'  and  to  define  them  by  refer-! 
ence  to  two  fundamental  concepts  for  which  I  have  been  inj 
the  habit  of  using  the  terms  'ritual  status'  and  'ritual  value'.! 
I  am  not  suggesting  that  these  are  the  best  terms  to  be  found; 
they  are  merely  the  best  that  I  have  been  able  to  find  up  to  the 
present.  In  such  a  science  as  ours  words  are  the  instrument 
of  analysis  and  we  should  always  be  prepared  to  discard  inferio: 
tools  for  superior  when  opportunity  arises. 

A  ritual  prohibition  is  a  rule  of  behaviour  which  is  associate 


\ 


TABOO  135 

with  a  belief  that  an  infraction  will  result  in  an  undesirable  change 
in  the  ritual  status  of  the  person  who  fails  to  keep  to  the  rule. 
This  change  of  ritual  status  is  conceived  in  many  different  ways 
in  different  societies,  but  everywhere  there  is  the  idea  that  it 
involves  the  likelihood  of  some  minor  or  major  misfortune  which 
will  befall  the  person  concerned. 

We  have  already  considered  one  example.  The  Polynesian 
who  touches  a  corpse  has,  according  to  Polynesian  belief,  under- 
gone what  I  am  calling  an  undesirable  change  of  ritual  status. 
The  misfortune  of  which  he  is  considered  to  be  in  danger  is 
illness,  and  he  therefore  takes  precautions  and  goes  through  a 
ritual  in  order  that  he  may  escape  the  danger  and  be  restored  to 
his  former  ritual  status. 

Let  us  consider  two  examples  of  different  kinds  from  con- 
temporary England.  There  are  some  people  who  think  that  one 
should  avoid  spilling  salt.  The  person  who  spills  salt  will  have 
bad  luck.  But  he  can  avoid  this  by  throwing  a  pinch  of  the  spilled 
salt  over  his  shoulder.  Putting  this  in  my  terminology  it  can  be 
said  that  spiUing  salt  produces  an  undesirable  change  in  the  ritual 
status  of  the  person  who  does  so,  and  that  he  is  restored  to  his 
normal  or  previous  ritual  status  by  the  positive  rite  of  throwing 
salt  over  his  shoulder. 

A  member  of  the  Roman  Catholic  Church,  unless  granted  a 
dispensation,  is  required  by  his  religion  to  abstain  from  eating 
meat  on  Fridays  and  during  Lent.  If  he  fails  to  observe  the  rule  he 
sins,  and  must  proceed,  as  in  any  other  sin,  to  confess  and  obtain 
absolution.  Different  as  this  is  in  important  ways  from  the  rule 
about  spilling  salt,  it  can  and  must  for  scientific  purposes  be 
regarded  as  belonging  to  the  same  general  class.  Eating  meat  on 
Friday  produces  in  the  person  who  does  so  an  undesirable  change 
of  ritual  status  which  requires  to  be  remedied  by  fixed  appropriate 
means. 

We  may  add  to  these  examples  two  others  from  other  societies. 
If  you  turn  to  the  fifth  chapter  of  Leviticus  you  will  find  that 
amongst  the  Hebrews  if  a  'soul'  touch  the  carcase  of  an  unclean 
beast  or  of  unclean  cattle,  or  of  unclean  creeping  things,  even  if 
he  is  unaware  that  he  does  so,  then  he  is  unclean  and  guilty  and 
has  sinned.  When  he  becomes  aware  of  his  sin  he  must  confess 
that  he  has  sinned  and  must  take  a  trespass  offering — a  female 
from  the  flock,  a  lamb  or  a  kid  of  the  goats — which  the  priest 


136  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

shall  sacrifice  to  make  an  atonement  for  the  sin  so  that  it  shall  be 
forgiven  him.  Here  the  change  in  ritual  status  through  touching 
an  unclean  carcase  is  described  by  the  terms  'sin',  'unclean' 
and  'guilty'. 

In  the  Kikuyu  tribe  of  East  Africa  the  word  thahu  denotes 
the  undesirable  ritual  status  that  results  from  failure  to  observe 
rules  of  ritual  avoidance.  It  is  believed  that  a  person  who  is  thahu 
will  be  ill  and  will  probably  die  unless  he  removes  the  thahu 
by  the  appropriate  ritual  remedies,  which  in  all  serious  cases 
require  the  services  of  a  priest  or  medicine  man.  Actions  which 
produce  this  condition  are  touching  or  carrying  a  corpse,  stepping 
over  a  corpse,  eating  food  from  a  cracked  pot,  coming  in  contact 
with  a  woman's  menstrual  discharge,  and  many  others.  Just 
as  among  the  Hebrews  a  soul  may  unwittingly  be  guilty  of  sin 
by  touching  in  ignorance  the  carcase  of  an  unclean  animal,  so 
amongst  the  Kikuyu  a  man  may  become  thahu  without  any 
voluntary  act  on  his  part.  If  an  elder  or  a  woman  when  coming 
out  of  the  hut  slips  and  falls  down  on  the  ground,  he  or  she  is 
thahu  and  lies  there  until  some  of  the  elders  of  the  neighbourhood 
come  and  sacrifice  a  sheep.  If  the  side-pole  of  a  bedstead  breaks, 
the  person  lying  on  it  is  thahu  and  must  be  purified.  If  the  drop- 
pings of  a  kite  or  crow  fall  on  a  person  he  is  thahu,  and  if  a  hyaena 
defaecates  in  a  village,  or  a  jackal  barks  therein,  the  village  and 
its  inhabitants  are  thahu. 

I  have  purposely  chosen  from  our  society  two  examples  of 
ritual  avoidances  which  are  of  very  difi^erent  kinds.  The  rule 
against  eating  meat  on  Friday  or  in  Lent  is  a  rule  of  religion,  as  is 
the  rule,  where  it  is  recognised,  against  playing  golf  or  tennis  on 
Sunday.  The  rule  against  spilling  salt,  I  suppose  it  will  be  agreed, 
is  non- religious.  Our  language  permits  us  to  make  this  distinction 
very  clearly,  for  infractions  of  the  rules  of  religion  are  sins,  while 
the  non-religious  avoidances  are  concerned  v.ith  good  and  bad 
luck.  Since  this  distinction  is  so  obvious  to  us  it  might  be  thought 
that  we  should  find  it  in  other  societies.  My  own  experience  is 
that  in  some  of  the  societies  with  which  I  am  acquainted  this 
distinction  between  sinful  acts  and  acts  that  bring  bad  luck 
cannot  be  made.  Several  anthropologists,  however,  have  attempted 
to  classify  rites  into  two  classes,  religious  rites  and  magical  rites. 

For  Emile  Durkheim  the  essential  distinction  is  that  religious 
rites  are  obligatory  within  a  religious  society  or  church,  while 


TABOO  137 

magical  rites  are  optional.  A  person  who  fails  in  religious  obser- 
vances is  guilty  of  wrong-doing,  whereas  one  who  does  not  observe 
the  precautions  of  magic  or  those  relating  to  luck  is  simply  acting 
foolishly.  This  distinction  is  of  considerable  theoretical  im- 
portance. It  is  difficult  to  apply  in  the  study  of  the  rites  of 
simple  societies. 

Sir  James  Frazer  defines  religion  as  'a  propitiation  or  con- 
ciliation of  superhuman  powers  which  are  believed  to  control 
nature  and  man',  and  regards  magic  as  the  erroneous  application 
of  the  notion  of  causality.  If  we  apply  this  to  ritual  prohibitions, 
we  may  regard  as  belonging  to  religion  those  rules  the  infraction 
of  which  produces  a  change  of  ritual  status  in  the  individual 
by  offending  the  superhuman  powers,  whereas  the  infraction 
of  a  rule  of  magic  would  be  regarded  as  resulting  immediately 
in  a  change  of  ritual  status,  or  in  the  misfortune  that  follows,  by  a 
process  of  hidden  causation.  Spilling  salt,  by  Sir  James  Frazer's 
definition,  is  a  question  of  magic,  while  eating  meat  on  Friday  is  a 
question  of  religion. 

An  attempt  to  apply  this  distinction  systematically  meets  with 
certain  difficulties.  Thus  with  regard  to  the  Maori  Sir  James 
Frazer  states  that  'the  ultimate  sanction  of  the  taboo,  in  other 
words,  that  which  engaged  the  people  to  observe  its  command- 
ments, was  a  firm  persuasion  that  any  breach  of  those  command- 
ments would  surely  and  speedily  be  punished  by  an  atua  or  ghost, 
who  would  afflict  the  sinner  with  a  painful  malady  till  he  died'. 
This  would  seem  to  make  the  Polynesian  taboo  a  matter  of  religion, 
not  of  magic.  But  my  own  observation  of  the  Polynesians  suggests 
to  me  that  in  general  the  native  conceives  of  the  change  in  his 
ritual  status  as  taking  place  as  the  immediate  result  of  such  an  act 
as  touching  a  corpse,  and  that  it  is  only  when  he  proceeds  to 
rationalise  the  whole  system  of  taboos  that  he  thinks  of  the  gods 
and  spirits — the  atiia — ^as  being  concerned.  Incidentally  it  should 
not  be  assumed  that  the  Polynesian  word  atua  or  otiia  always 
refers  to  a  personal  spiritual  being. 

Of  the  various  ways  of  distinguishing  magic  and  religion  I 
will  mention  only  one  more.  For  Professor  Malinowski  a  rite  is 
magical  when  'it  has  a  definite  practical  purpose  which  is  known 
to  all  who  practise  it  and  can  be  easily  elicited  from  any  native 
informant',  while  a  rite  is  religious  if  it  is  simply  expressive  and 
has  no  purpose,  being  not  a  means  to  an  end  but  an  end  in  itself. 


138  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

A  difficulty  in  applying  this  criterion  is  due  to  uncertainty  as  t 
what  is  meant  by  'definite  practical  purpose'.  To  avoid  the  ba 
luck  which  results  from  spilling  salt  is,  I  suppose,  a  practica; 
purpose  though  not  very  definite.  The  desire  to  please  God  ii 
all  our  actions  and  thus  escape  some  period  of  Purgatory  i 
perhaps  definite  enough,  but  Professor  Malinowski  may  regard  i 
as  not  practical.  What  shall  we  say  of  the  desire  of  the  Polynesia 
to  avoid  sickness  and  possible  death  which  he  gives  as  his  reaso 
for  not  touching  chiefs,  corpses  and  newly-born  babies? 

Seeing  that  there  is  this  absence  of  agreement  as  to  th 
definitions  of  magic  and  religion  and  the  nature  of  the  distinctic; 
between  them,  and  seeing  that  in  many  instances  whether  v 
call  a  particular  rite  magical  or  religious  depends  on  which  ' 
the  various  proposed  definitions  we  accept,  the  only  soue 
procedure,  at  any  rate  in  the  present  state  of  anthropologic 
knowledge,  is  to  avoid  as  far  as  possible  the  use  of  the  terms  ; 
question  until  there  is  some  general  agreement  about  thei 
Certainly  the  distinctions  made  by  Durkheim  and  Frazer  ai 
Malinowski  may  be  theoretically  significant,  even  though  th^ 
are  difficult  to  apply  universally.  Certainly,  also,  there  is  ne< 
for  a  systematic  classification  of  rites,  but  a  satisfacto? 
classification  will  be  fairly  complex  and  a  simple  dichoton 
between  magic  and  religion  does  not  carry  us  very  far  towards  : 

Another    distinction   which   we    make    in    our    own   sociei 
within  the  field  of  ritual  avoidances  is  between  the  holy  and  tl 
unclean.  Certain  things  must  be  treated  with  respect  because  the 
are  holy,  others  because  they  are  unclean.  But,  as  Robertsc 
Smith  and  Sir  James  Frazer  have  shown,  there  are  many  societio 
in  which  this  distinction  is  entirely  unrecognised.  The  Polynesian 
for  example,  does  not  think  of  a  chief  or  a  temple  as  holy  and 
corpse  as  unclean.  He  thinks  of  them  all  as  things  dangerous.  A 
example  from  Hawaii  will  illustrate  this  fundamental  identit 
of  holiness  and  uncleanness.  There,  in  former  times,  if  a  commom 
committed  incest  with  his  sister  he  became  kapu  (the  Hawaiian; 
form  of  tabu).  His  presence  was  dangerous  in  the  extreme  for  tbj. 
whole  community,  and  since  he  could  not  be  purified  he  was  pi 
to  death.  But  if  a  chief  of  high  rank,  who,  by  reason  of  his  rank  wa^ 
of  course,  sacred  (kapu),  married  his  sister  he  became  still  more  s(V 
An  extreme  sanctity  or  untouchability  attached  to  a  chief  born  of  I 
brother  and  sister  who  were  themselves  the  children  of  a  brothel 


TABOO  139 

and  sister.  The  sanctity  of  such  a  chief  and  the  uncleanness  of  the 
person  put  to  death  for  incest  have  the  same  source  and  are 
the  same  thing.  They  are  both  denoted  by  saying  that  the  person 
is  kapu.  In  studying  the  simpler  societies  it  is  essential  that  we 
should  carefully  avoid  thinking  of  their  behaviour  and  ideas  in 
terms  of  our  own  ideas  of  holiness  and  uncleanness.  Since  most 
people  find  this  difficult  it  is  desirable  to  have  terms  which  we  can 
use  that  do  not  convey  this  connotation.  Durkheim  and  others  have 
used  the  word  'sacred'  as  an  inclusive  term  for  the  holy  and  the 
unclean  together.  This  is  easier  to  do  in  Frtnch  than  in  English, 
and  has  some  justification  in  the  fact  that  the  Latin  sacer  did  apply 
to  holy  things  such  as  the  gods  and  also  to  accursed  things  such  as 
persons  guilty  of  certain  crimes.  But  there  is  certainly  a  tendency 
in  English  to  identify  sacred  with  holy.  I  think  that  it  will  greatly 
aid  clear  thinking  if  we  adopt  some  wide  inclusive  term  which  does 
not  have  any  undesirable  connotation.  I  venture  to  propose  the 
term  'ritual  value'. 

Anything — a  person,  a  material  thing,  a  place,  a  word  or  name, 
an  occasion  or  event,  a  day  of  the  week  or  a  period  of  the  year — 
which  is  the  object  of  a  ritual  avoidance  or  taboo  can  be  said  to  have 
ritual  value.  Thus  in  Polynesia  chiefs,  corpses  and  ncMly-born 
babies  have  ritual  value.  For  some  people  in  England  salt  has 
ritual  value.  For  Christians  all  Sundays  and  Good  Friday  have 
ritual  value,  and  for  Jews  all  Saturdays  and  the  Day  of  Atonement. 
The  ritual  value  is  exhibited  in  the  behaviour  adopted  towards 
the  object  or  occasion  in  question.  Ritual  values  are  exhibited 
not  only  in  negative  ritual  but  also  in  positive  ritual,  being 
possessed  by  the  objects  towards  which  positive  rites  are  directed 
and  also  by  objects,  words  or  places  used  in  the  rites.  A  large  class 
of  positive  rites,  those  of  consecration  or  sacralisation,  have  for 
their  purpose  to  endow  objects  with  ritual  value.  It  may  be  noted 
that  in  general  anything  that  has  value  in  positive  ritual  is  also  the 
object  of  some  sort  of  ritual  avoidance  or  at  the  very  least  of  ritual 
respect. 

The  word  'value',  as  I  am  using  it,  always  refers  to  a  relation 
between  a  subject  and  an  object.  The  relation  can  be  stated  in  two 
ways  by  saying  either  that  the  object  has  a  value  for  the  subject, 
or  that  the  subject  has  an  interest  in  the  object.  We  can  use  the 
terms  in  this  way  to  refer  to  any  act  of  behaviour  towards  an  object. 
The  relation  is  exhibited  in  and  defined  by  the  behaviour.  The 


140  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION  IN  PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

words  'interest'  and  'value'  provide  a  convenient  shorthand  by 
which  we  can  describe  the  reaUty,  which  consists  of  acts  of  be- 
haviour and  the  actual  relations  between  subjects  and  objects 
which  those  acts  of  behaviour  reveal.  If  Jack  loves  Jill,  then  Jill 
has  the  value  of  a  loved  object  for  Jack,  and  Jack  has  a  recognisable 
interest  in  Jill.  When  I  am  hungry  I  have  an  interest  in  food,  and  a 
good  meal  has  an  immediate  value  for  me  that  it  does  not  have  at 
other  times.  My  toothache  has  a  value  to  me  as  something  that  I 
am  interested  in  getting  rid  of  as  quickly  as  possible, 

A  social  system  can  be  conceived  and  studied  as  a  system  of 
values.  A  society  consists  of  a  number  of  individuals  bound  together 
in  a  network  of  social  relations.  A  social  relation  exists  between 
two  or  more  persons  when  there  is  some  harmonisation  of  their 
individual  interests,  by  some  convergence  of  interest  and  by 
limitation  or  adjustment  of  divergent  interests.  An  interest  is 
always  the  interest  of  an  individual.  Two  individuals  may  have 
similar  interests.  Similar  interests  do  not  in  themselves  constitute 
a  social  relation;  two  dogs  may  have  a  similar  interest  in  the  same 
bone  and  the  result  may  be  a  dog-fight.  But  a  society  cannot  exist 
except  on  the  basis  of  a  certain  measure  of  similarity  in  the 
interests  of  its  members.  Putting  this  in  terms  of  value,  the 
first  necessary  condition  of  the  existence  of  a  society  is  that 
the  individual  members  shall  agree  in  some  measure  in  the  values 
that  they  recognise. 

Any  particular  society  is  characterised  by  a  certain  set  of 
values — moral,  aesthetic,  economic,  etc.  In  a  simple  society  there 
is  a  fair  amount  of  agreement  amongst  the  members  in  their 
evaluations,  though  of  course  the  agreement  is  never  absolute. 
In  a  complex  modern  society  we  find  much  more  disagreement 
if  we  consider  the  society  as  a  whole,  but  we  may  find  a  closer 
measure  of  agreement  amongst  the  members  of  a  group  or  class 
within  the  society. 

While  some  measure  of  agreement  about  values,  some  simi- 
larity of  interests,  is  a  prerequisite  of  a  social  system,  social 
relations  involve  more  than  this.  They  require  the  existence  of 
common  interests  and  of  social  values.  When  two  or  more  persons 
have  a  common  interest  in  the  same  object  and  are  aware  of  their 
community  of  interest  a  social  relation  is  established.  They  form, 
whether  for  a  moment  or  for  a  long  period,  an  association,  and  the 
object  may  be  said  to  have  a  social  value.  For  a  man  and  his  wife 


TABOO  141 

the  birth  of  a  child,  the  child  itself  and  its  well-being  and  happi- 
ness or  its  death,  are  objects  of  a  common  interest  which  binds 
them  together  and  they  thus  have,  for  the  association  formed  by 
the  two  persons,  social  value.  By  this  definition  an  object  can  only 
have  a  social  value  for  an  association  of  persons.  In  the  simplest 
possible  instance  we  have  a  triadic  relation;  Subject  i  and  Subject  2 
are  both  interested  in  the  same  way  in  the  Object  and  each  of  the 
Subjects  has  an  interest  in  the  other,  or  at  any  rate  in  certain 
items  of  the  behaviour  of  the  other,  namely  those  directed  towards 
the  object.  To  avoid  cumbersome  circumlocutions  it  is  convenient 
to  speak  of  the  object  as  having  a  social  value  for  any  one  subject 
involved  in  such  a  relation,  but  it  must  be  remembered  that  this 
is  a  loose  way  of  speaking. 

It  is  perhaps  necessary  for  the  avoidance  of  misunderstanding 
to  add  that  a  social  system  also  requires  that  persons  should  be 
objects  of  interest  to  other  persons.  In  relations  of  friendship 
or  love  each  of  two  persons  has  a  value  for  the  other.  In  certain 
kinds  of  groups  each  member  is  an  object  of  interest  for  all  the 
others,  and  each  member  therefore  has  a  social  value  for  the  group 
as  a  whole.  Further,  since  there  are  negative  values  as  well  as 
positive,  persons  may  be  united  or  associated  by  their  antagonism 
to  other  persons.  For  the  members  of  an  anti-Comintern  pact  the 
Comintern  has  a  specific  social  value. 

Amongst  the  members  of  a  society  we  find  a  certain  measure  of 
agreement  as  to  the  ritual  value  they  attribute  to  objects  of  different 
kinds.  We  also  find  that  most  of  these  ritual  values  are  social 
values  as  defined  above.  Thus  for  a  local  totemic  clan  in  Australia 
the  totem-centres,  the  natural  species  associated  with  them,  i.e. 
the  totems,  and  the  myths  and  rites  that  relate  thereto,  have  a 
specific  social  value  for  the  clan;  the  common  interest  in  them 
binds  the  individuals  together  into  a  firm  and  lasting  association. 

Ritual  values  exist  in  every  known  society,  and  show  an  im- 
mense diversity  as  we  pass  from  one  society  to  another.  The 
problem  of  a  natural  science  of  society  (and  it  is  as  such  that  I 
regard  social  anthropology)  is  to  discover  the  deeper,  not  im- 
mediately perceptible,  uniformities  beneath  the  superficial  differ- 
ences. This  is,  of  course,  a  highly  complex  problem  which  will 
require  the  studies  begun  by  Sir  James  Frazer  and  others  to  be 
continued  by  many  investigators  over  many  years.  The  ultimate 
aim  should  be,  I  think,  to  find  some  relatively  adequate  answer 


142  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

to  the  question — What  is  the  relation  of  ritual  and  ritual  values 
to  the  essential  constitution  of  human  society?  I  have  chosen  a 
particular  approach  to  this  study  which  I  beheve  to  be  promising — 
to  investigate  in  a  few  societies  studied  as  thoroughly  as  possible 
the  relations  of  ritual  values  to  other  values  including  moral  and 
aesthetic  values.  In  the  present  lecture,  however,  it  is  only  one 
small  part  of  this  study  in  which  I  seek  to  interest  you — the 
question  of  a  relation  between  ritual  values  and  social  values. 

One  way  of  approaching  the  study  of  ritual  is  by  the  con- 
sideration of  the  purposes  or  reasons  for  the  rites.  If  one  examines 
the  literature  of  anthropology  one  finds  this  approach  very 
frequently  adopted.  It  is  by  far  the  least  profitable,  though  the 
one  that  appeals  most  to  common  sense.  Sometimes  the  purpose 
of  a  rite  is  obvious,  or  a  reason  may  be  volunteered  by  those  who 
practise  it.  Sometimes  the  anthropologist  has  to  ask  the  reason, 
and  in  such  circumstances  it  may  happen  that  different  reasons 
are  given  by  different  informants.  What  is  fundamentally  the 
same  rite  in  two  different  societies  may  have  different  purposes 
or  reasons  in  the  one  and  in  the  other.  The  reasons  given  by 
the  members  of  a  community  for  any  custom  they  observe  are 
important  data  for  the  anthropologist.  But  it  is  to  fall  into  grievous 
error  to  suppose  that  they  give  a  valid  explanation  of  the  custom. 
What  is  entirely  inexcusable  is  for  the  anthropologist,  when  he 
cannot  get  from  the  people  themselves  a  reason  for  their  behaviour 
which  seems  to  him  satisfactory,  to  attribute  to  them  some  purpose 
or  reason  on  the  basis  of  his  own  preconceptions  about  human 
motives.  I  could  adduce  many  instances  of  this  from  the  literature 
of  ethnography,  but  I  prefer  to  illustrate  what  I  mean  by  an 
anecdote. 

A  Queenslander  met  a  Chinese  who  was  taking  a  bowl  of 
cooked  rice  to  place  on  his  brother's  grave.  The  Australian  in 
jocular  tones  asked  if  he  supposed  that  his  brother  would  come 
and  eat  the  rice.  The  reply  was  'No!  We  offer  rice  to  people  as  an 
expression  of  friendship  and  affection.  But  since  you  speak  as  you 
do  I  suppose  that  you  in  this  country  place  flowers  on  the  graves 
of  your  dead  in  the  belief  that  they  will  enjoy  looking  at  them  and 
smelling  their  sweet  perfume.' 

So  far  as  ritual  avoidances  are  concerned  the  reasons  for  them 
may  vary  from  a  very  vague  idea  that  some  sort  of  misfortune  or 
ill-luck,  not  defined  as  to  its  kind,  is  likely  to  befall  anyone  who  isit 


TABOO  143 

fails  to  observe  the  taboo,  to  a  belief  that  non-observance  will 
produce  some  quite  specific  and  undesirable  result.  Thus  an 
Australian  aborigine  told  me  that  if  he  spoke  to  any  woman  who 
stood  in  the  relation  of  mother-in-law  to  him  his  hair  would  turn 
grey.i 

The  very  common  tendency  to  look  for  the  explanation  of 
ritual  actions  in  their  purpose  is  the  result  of  a  false  assimilation 
of  them  to  what  may  be  called  technical  acts.  In  any  technical 
activity  an  adequate  statement  of  the  purpose  of  any  particular 
act  or  series  of  acts  constitutes  by  itself  a  sufficient  explanation. 
But  ritual  acts  differ  from  technical  acts  in  having  in  all  instances 
some  expressive  or  symbolic  element  in  them. 

A  second  approach  to  the  study  of  ritual  is  therefore  by  a 
consideration  not  of  their  purpose  or  reason  but  of  their  meaning. 
I  am  here  using  the  words  symbol  and  meaning  as  coincident. 
Whatever  has  a  meaning  is  a  symbol  and  the  meaning  is  whatever 
is  expressed  by  the  symbol. 

But  how  are  we  to  discover  meanings?  They  do  not  lie  on  the 
surface.  There  is  a  sense  in  which  people  always  know  the  meaning 
of  their  own  symbols,  but  they  do  so  intuitively  and  can  rarely 
express  their  understanding  in  words.  Shall  we  therefore  be 
reduced  to  guessing  at  meanings  as  some  anthropologists  have 
guessed  at  reasons  and  purposes?  I  think  not.  For  as  long  as  we 
admit  guess-work  of  any  kind  social  anthropology^  cannot  be  a 
science.  There  are,  I  believe,  methods  of  determining,  with  some 
fair  degree  of  probability,  the  meanings  of  rites  and  other  s}Tnbols. 

There  is  still  a  third  approach  to  the  study  of  rites.  We  can 
consider  the  effects  of  the  rite — not  the  effects  that  it  is  supposed 
to  produce  by  the  people  who  practise  it  but  the  effects  that  it  does 
actually  produce.  A  rite  has  immediate  or  direct  effects  on  the 
persons  who  are  in  any  way  directly  concerned  in  it,  which  we  may 
call,  for  lack  of  a  better  term,  the  psychological  effects.  But  there 

1  In  case  it  may  be  thought  that  this  is  an  inadequate  supernatural  punish- 
ment for  a  serious  breach  of  rules  of  proper  behaviour  a  few  words  of  ex- 
planation are  necessary.  Grey  hair  comes  with  old  age  and  is  thought  to  be 
usually  associated  with  loss  of  sexual  potency.  It  is  thus  premature  old  age 
with  its  disadvantages  but  without  the  advantages  that  usually  accompany 
seniority  that  threatens  the  man  who  fails  to  observe  the  rules  of  avoidance, 
♦be  other  hand  when  a  man's  hair  is  grey  and  his  wife's  mother  has  passed 
perge  of  child-bearing  the  taboo  is  relaxed  so  that  the  relatives  may  talk 
i    Sacher  if  they  wish. 


144  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

are  also  secondary  effects  upon  the  social  structure,  i.e.  the  network 
of  social  relations  binding  individuals  together  in  an  ordered  life. 
These  we  may  call  the  social  effects.  By  considering  the  psychological 
effects  of  a  rite  we  may  succeed  in  defining  its  psychological  function; 
by  considering  the  social  effects  we  may  discover  its  social  function. 
Clearly  it  is  impossible  to  discover  the  social  function  of  a  rite  with- 
out taking  into  account  its  usual  or  average  psychological  effects. 
But  it  is  possible  to  discuss  the  psychological  effects  while  more 
or  less  completely  ignoring  the  more  remote  sociological  effects, 
and  this  is  often  done  in  what  is  called  'functional  anthropology'. 

Let  us  suppose  that  we  wish  to  investigate  in  Australian  tribes 
the  totemic  rites  of  a  kind  widely  distributed  over  a  large  part  of 
the  continent.  The  ostensible  purpose  of  these  rites,  as  stated 
by  the  natives  themselves,  is  to  renew  or  maintain  some  part  of 
nature,  such  as  a  species  of  animal  or  plant,  or  rain,  or  hot  or 
cold  weather.  With  reference  to  this  purpose  we  have  to  say  that 
from  our  point  of  view  the  natives  are  mistaken,  that  the  rites 
do  not  actually  do  what  they  are  believed  to  do.  The  rain-making 
ceremony  does  not,  we  think,  actually  bring  rain.  In  so  far  as  the 
rites  are  performed  for  a  purpose  they  are  futile,  based  on  erroneous 
belief.  I  do  not  believe  that  there  is  any  scientific  value  in  attempts 
to  conjecture  processes  of  reasoning  which  might  be  supposed  to 
have  led  to  these  errors. 

The  rites  are  easily  perceived  to  be  symbolic,  and  we  may 
therefore  investigate  their  meaning.  To  do  this  we  have  to  examine 
a  considerable  number  of  them  and  we  then  discover  that  there  is 
a  certain  body  of  ritual  idiom  extending  from  the  west  coast  of  the 
continent  to  the  east  coast  with  some  local  variations.  Since  each 
rite  has  a  myth  associated  with  it  we  have  similarly  to  investigate 
the  meanings  of  the  myths.  As  a  result  we  find  that  the  meaning  of 
any  single  rite  becomes  clear  in  the  light  of  a  cosmolog}^  a  body 
of  ideas  and  beliefs  about  nature  and  human  society,  which,  so 
far  as  its  most  general  features  are  concerned,  is  current  in  all 
Australian  tribes. 

The  immediate  psychological  effects  of  the  rites  can  be  to 
some  extent  observed  by  watching  and  talking  to  the  performers. 
The  ostensible  purpose  of  the  rite  is  certainly  present  in  their 
minds,  but  so  also  is  that  complex  set  of  cosmological  beliefs  by 
reference  to  which  the  rite  has  a  meaning.  Certainly  a  pc  oon 
performing  the  rite,  even  if,  as  sometimes  happens,  he  perfon-lis  it 


TABOO  145 

alone,  derives  therefrom  a  definite  feeling  of  satisfaction,  but  it 
would  be  entirely  false  to  imagine  that  this  is  simply  because  he 
believes  that  he  has  helped  to  provide  a  more  abundant  supply 
of  food  for  himself  and  his  fellow-tribesmen.  His  satisfaction  is  in 
having  performed  a  ritual  duty,  we  might  say  a  religious  duty. 
Putting  in  my  own  words  what  I  judge,  from  my  own  observations, 
to  express  what  the  native  feels,  I  would  say  that  in  the  performance 
of  the  rite  he  has  made  that  small  contribution,  which  it  is  both 
his  privilege  and  his  duty  to  do,  to  the  maintenance  of  that  order 
of  the  universe  of  which  man  and  nature  are  interdependent 
parts.  The  satisfaction  which  he  thus  receives  gives  the  rite  a 
special  value  for  him.  In  some  instances  with  which  I  am  ac- 
quainted of  the  last  survivor  of  a  totemic  group  who  still  continues 
to  perform  the  totemic  rites  by  himself,  it  is  this  satisfaction  that 
constitutes  apparently  the  sole  motive  for  his  action. 

To  discover  the  social  function  of  the  totemic  rites  we  have 
to  consider  the  whole  body  of  cosmological  ideas  of  which  each 
rite  is  a  partial  expression.  I  believe  that  it  is  possible  to  show 
that  the  social  structure  of  an  Australian  tribe  is  connected  in  a 
very  special  way  with  these  cosmological  ideas  and  that  the  main- 
tenance of  its  continuity  depends  on  keeping  them  alive,  by 
their  regular  expression  in  myth  and  rite. 

Thus  any  satisfactory  study  of  the  totemic  rites  of  Australia 
must  be  based  not  simply  on  the  consideration  of  their  ostensible 
purpose  and  their  psychological  function,  or  on  an  analysis  of  the 
motives  of  the  individuals  who  perform  the  rites,  but  on  the 
discovery  of  their  meaning  and  of  their  social  function. 

It  may  be  that  some  rites  have  no  social  function.  This  may 
be  the  case  with  such  taboos  as  that  against  spilling  salt  in  our  own 
society.  Nevertheless,  the  method  of  investigating  rites  and  ritual 
values  that  I  have  found  most  profitable  during  work  extending 
over  more  than  thirty  years  is  to  study  rites  as  symbolic  expressions 
and  to  seek  to  discover  their  social  functions.  This  method  is  not 
new  except  in  so  far  as  it  is  applied  to  the  comparative  study  of 
many  societies  of  diverse  types.  It  was  applied  by  Chinese  thinkers 
to  their  own  ritual  more  than  twenty  centuries  ago. 

In  China,  in  the  fifth  and  sixth  centuries  B.C.,  Confucius  and 
his  followers  insisted  on  the  great  importance  of  the  proper 
performance  of  ritual,  such  as  funeral  and  mourning  rites  and 
sacrifices.  After  Confucius  there  came  the  reformer  Mo  Ti  who 


/ 


146  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

taught  a  combination  of  altruism — love  for  all  men — and  utili- 
tarianism. He  held  that  funeral  and  mourning  rites  were  useless 
and  interfered  with  useful  activities  and  should  therefore   be 
abolished  or  reduced  to  a  minimum.  In  the  third  and  second 
centuries  B.C.,  the  Confucians,  Hsiin  Tze  and  the  compilers  of  the 
Li  Chi  (Book  of  Rites),  replied  to  Mo  Ti  to  the  eifect  that  though 
these  rites  might  have  no  utilitarian  purpose  they  none  the  less 
had  a  very  important  social  function.  Briefly  the  theory  is  that  the 
rites  are  the  orderly  (the  Li  Chi  says  the  beautified)  expression  of 
feelings  appropriate  to  a  social  situation.  They  thus  serve  to 
regulate  and  refine  human  emotions.  We  may  say  that  partaking 
in  the  performance  of  rites  serves  to  cultivate  in  the  individual 
sentiments  on  whose  existence  the  social  order  itself  depends. 
~"  -.  Let  us  consider  the  meaning  and  social  function  of  an  extremely 
simple  example  of  ritual.  In  the  Andaman  Islands  when  a  woman 
is  expecting  a  baby  a  name  is  given  to  it  while  it  is  still  in  the 
I  womb.  From  that  time  until  some  weeks  after  the  baby  is  born 
1  nobody  is  allowed  to  use  the  personal  name  of  either  the  father  or 
{  the  mother;  they  can  be  referred  to  by  teknonymy,  i.e.  in  terms  of 
\  their  relation  to  the  child.  During  this  period  both  the  parents  are 
'  required  to  abstain  from  eating  certain  foods  which  they  may 
i^^^ely  eat  at  other  times. 

/""^  did  not  obtain  from  the  Andamanese  any  statement  of  the 
(purpose  or  reason  for  this  avoidance  of  names.  Assuming  that  the 
lact  is  symbolic,  what  method,  other  than  that  of  guessing,  is  there 
jof  arriving  at  the  meaning?  I  suggest  that  we  may  start  with  a 
general  working  hypothesis  that  when,  in  a  single  society,  the 
(Same  s)rmbol  is  used  in  different  contexts  or  on  different  kinds  of 
[occasions  there  is  some  common  element  of  meaning,  and  that 
by  comparing  together  the  various  uses  of  the  symbol  we  may  be 
!  able  to  discover  what  the  common  element  is.  This  is  precisely  the 
j  method  that  we  adopt  in  studying  an  unrecorded  spoken  language 
/  in  order  to  discover  the  meanings  of  words  and  morphemes. 
'         In  the  Andamans  the  name  of  a  dead  person  is  avoided  from 
the  occurrence  of  the  death  to  the  conclusion  of  mourning;  the 
name  of  a  person  mourning  for  a  dead  relative  is  not  used;  there  is 
avoidance  of  the  name  of  a  youth  or  girl  who  is  passing  through 
the  ceremonies  that  take  place  at  adolescence;  a  bride  or  bride- 
groom is  not  spoken  of  or  to  by  his  or  her  own  name  for  a  short 
time  after  the  marriage.  For  the  Andamanese  the  personal  name 


TABOO  14* 

is  a  symbol  of  the  social  personality,  i.e.  of  the  position  that  an 
individual  occupies  in  the  social  structure  and  the  social  life. 
The  avoidance  of  a  personal  name  is  a  symbolic  recognition  of  the 
fact  that  at  the  time  the  person  is  not  occupying  a  normal  position 
in  the  social  life.  It  may  be  added  that  a  person  whose  name  is 
thus  temporarily  out  of  use  is  regarded  as  having  for  the  time  an 
abnormal  ritual  status. 

Turning  now  to  the  rule  as  to  avoiding  certain  foods,  if  the 
Andaman  Islanders  are  asked  what  would  happen  if  the  father 
or  mother  broke  his  taboo  the  usual  answer  is  that  he  or  she  would 
be  ill,  though  one  or  two  of  my  informants  thought  it  might  per- 
haps also  affect  the  child.  This  is  simply  one  instance  of  a  standard 
formula  which  applies  to  a  number  of  ritual  prohibitions.  Thus 
persons  in  mourning  for  a  relative  may  not  eat  pork  and  turtle,  the 
most  important  flesh  foods,  and  the  reason  given  is  that  if  they 
did  they  would  be  ill. 

To  discover  the  meaning  of  this  avoidance  of  foods  by  the 
parents  we  can  apply  the  same  method  as  in  reference  to  the 
avoidance  of  their  names.  There  are  similar  rules  for  mourners, 
for  women  during  menstruation,  and  for  youths  and  girls  during 
the  period  of  adolescence.  But  for  a  full  demonstration  we  have 
to  consider  the  place  of  foods  in  Andamanese  ritual  as  a  w'hole, 
and  for  an  examination  of  this  I  must  refer  to  v.  hat  I  have  already 
written  on  the  subject. 

I  should  like  to  draw  your  attention  to  another  point  in  the 
method  by  W'hich  it  is  possible  to  test  our  hypotheses  as  to  the 
meanings  of  rites.  We  take  the  different  occasions  on  which  two 
rites  are  associated  together,  for  example  the  association  of  the 
avoidance  of  a  person's  name  with  the  avoidance  by  that  person  of 
certain  foods,  which  we  find  in  the  instance  of  mourners  on  the  one 
hand  and  the  expectant  mother  and  father  on  the  other.  We  must 
assume  that  for  the  Andamanese  there  is  some  important  similarity 
between  these  two  kinds  of  occasions — birth  and  death — by 
virtue  of  which  they  have  similar  ritual  values.  We  cannot  rest 
content  with  any  interpretation  of  the  taboos  at  childbirth  unless 
there  is  a  parallel  interpretation  of  those  relating  to  mourners. 
In  the  terms  I  am  using  here  we  can  say  that  in  the  Andamans  the 
relatives  of  a  recently  dead  person,  and  the  father  and  mother  of 
a  child  that  is  about  to  be,  or  has  recently  been,  born,  are  in  an 
abnormal  ritual  status.  This  is  recognised  or  indicated  by  the 


148  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

avoidance  of  their  names.  They  are  regarded  as  hkely  to  suffer 
some  misfortune,  some  bad  luck,  if  you  will,  unless  they  observe 
certain  prescribed  ritual  precautions  of  which  the  avoidance  of 
certain  foods  is  one.  In  the  Andaman  Islands  the  danger  in  such 
instances  is  thought  of  as  the  danger  of  illness.  This  is  the  case  also 
with  the  Polynesian  belief  about  the  ritual  status  of  anyone  who 
has  touched  a  corpse  or  a  newly-born  baby.  It  is  to  be  noted  that 
for  the  Polynesians  as  well  as  for  the  Andamanese  the  occasion  of 
a  birth  has  a  similar  ritual  value  to  that  of  a  death. 

The  interpretation  of  the  taboos  at  childbirth  at  which  we 
arrive  by  studying  it  in  relation  to  the  whole  system  of  ritual 
values  of  the  Andamanese  is  too  complex  to  be  stated  here  in 
full.  Clearly,  however,  they  express,  in  accordance  with  Anda- 
manese ritual  idiom,  a  common  concern  in  the  event.  The  parents 
show  their  concern  by  avoiding  certain  foods;  their  friends  show 
theirs  by  avoiding  the  parents'  personal  names.  By  virtue  of 
these  taboos  the  occasion  acquires  a  certain  social  value,  as  that 
term  has  been  defined  above. 

There  is  one  theory  that  might  seem  to  be  applicable  to  our 
example.  It  is  based  on  a~-hy;pothesis  as  to  the  psychological 
function  of  a  class  of  rites.  The  theory  is  that  in  certain  circum- 
stances the  individual  humaiTbeing  is  anxious  about  the  outcome 
of  some  event  or  activity  because  it  depends  to  some  extent  on 
conditions  that  he  cannot  control  by  any  technical  means.  He 
therefore  observes  some  rite  which,  since  he  believes  it  will  ensure 
good  luck,  serves  to  reassure  hinDThus  an  aeronaut  takes  with 
him  in  a  plane  a  mascot  which  he  believes  will  protect  him  from 
accident  and  thus  carries  out  his  flight  with  confidence. 

The  theory  has  a  respectable  antiquity.  It  was  perhaps  implied 
in  the  Primus  in  orbe  deos  fecit  timor  of  Petronius  and  Statins. 
It  has  taken  various  forms  from  Hume's  explanation  of  religion 
to  Malinowski's  explanation  of  Trobriand  magic.  It  can  be  made 
so  plausible  by  a  suitable  selection  of  illustrations  that  it  is  neces- 
sary to  examine  it  with  particular  care  and  treat  it  with  reasonable 
scepticism.  For  there  is  always  the  danger  that  we  may  be  taken 
in  by  the  plausibility  of  a  theory  that  ultimately  proves  to  be 
unsound. 

I  think  that  for  certain  rites  it  would  be  easy  to  maintain  with 
equal  plausibility  an  exactly  contrary  theory,  namely,  that  if  it 
were  not  for  the  existence  of  the  rite  and  the  beliefs  associated 


TABOO  149 

with  it  the  individual  would  feel  no  anxiety,  and  that  the  psycho- 
logical effect  of  the  rite  is  to  create  in  him  a  sense  of  insecurity  or 
danger.  It  seems  very  unlikely  that  an  Andaman  Islander  would 
think  that  it  is  dangerous  to  eat  dugong  or  pork  or  turtle  meat  if  it 
were  not  for  the  existence  of  a  specific  body  of  ritual  the  ostensible 
purpose  of  which  is  to  protect  him  from  those  dangers.  Many 
hundreds  of  similar  instances  could  be  mentioned  from  all  over 
the  world. 

Thus,  while  one  anthropological  theory  is  that  magic  and 
religion  give  men  confidence,  comfort  and  a  sense  of  security,^ 
it  could  equally  well  be  argued  that  they  give  men  fears  and  anxieties 
from  which  they  would  otherwise  be  free — the  fear  of  black 
magic  or  of  spirits,  fear  of  God,  of  the  Devil,  of  Hell. 

Actually  in  our  fears  or  anxieties  as  well  as  in  our  hopes  we 
are  conditioned  (as  the  phrase  goes)  by  the  community  in  which 
we  live.  And  it  is  largely  by  the  sharing  of  hopes  and  fears,  by 
what  I  have  called  common  concern  in  events  or  eventualities,  that 
human  beings  are  linked  together  in  temporary  or  permanent 
associations. 

To  return  to  the  Andamanese  taboos  at  childbirth,  there  are 
difficulties  in  supposing  that  they  are  means  by  which  parents 
reassure  themselves  against  the  accidents  that  may  interfere  with  a 
successful  delivery.  If  the  prospective  father  fails  to  observe  the 
i  food  taboo  it  is  he  who  will  be  sick,  according  to  the  general 
Andamanese  opinion.  Moreover,  he  must  continue  to  observe 
the  taboos  after  the  child  is  safely  delivered.  Further,  how  are  we 
to  provide  a  parallel  explanation  of  the  similar  taboos  observed 
by  a  person  mourning  for  a  dead  relative? 

The  taboos  associated  with  pregnancy  and  parturition  are 
often  explained  in  terms  of  the  hypothesis  I  have  mentioned. 
A  father,  naturally  anxious  at  the  outcome  of  an  event  over  which 
he  does  not  have  a  technical  control  and  which  is  subject  to 
hazard,  reassures  himself  by  observing  some  taboo  or  carr^^ing  out 
some  magical  action.  He  may  avoid  certain  foods.  He  may  avoid 
making  nets  or  tying  knots,  or  he  may  go  round  the  house  untying 
all  knots  and  opening  any  locked  or  closed  boxes  or  containers. 

I  wish  to  arouse  in  your  minds,  if  it  is  not  already  there,  a 
suspicion  that  both  the  general  theory  and  this  special  application 

^  This  theory  has  been  formulated  by  Loisy,  and  for  magic  has  been  adopted 
by  MaHnowski. 


150  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

of  it  do  not  give  the  whole  truth  and  indeed  may  not  be  true  at  all. 
Scepticism  of  plausible  but  unproved  hypotheses  is  essential  in 
every  science.  There  is  at  least  good  ground  for  suspicion  in  the 
fact  that  the  theory  has  so  far  been  considered  in  reference  to 
facts  that  seem  to  fit  it,  and  no  systematic  attempt  has  been  made, 
so  far  as  I  am  aware,  to  look  for  facts  that  do  not  fit.  That  there 
are  many  such  I  am  satisfied  from  my  own  studies. 

/The  alternative  hypothesis  which  I  am  presenting  for  con- 
sideration is  as  follows.  In  a  given  community  it  is  appropriate 
that  an  expectant  father  should  feel  concern  or  at  least  should 
make  an  appearance  of  doing  so.  Some  suitable  symbolic  ex- 
pression of  his  concern  is  found  in  terms  of  the  general  ritual 
or  symbolic  idiom  of  the  society,  and  it  is  felt  generally  that  a  man 
in  that  situation  ought  to  carry  out  the  symbolic  or  ritual  actions 
or  abstentions.  For  every  rule  that  ought  to  be  observed  there  must 
be  some  sort  of  sanction  or  reason.  For  acts  that  patently  affect 
other  persons  the  moral  and  legal  sanctions  provide  a  generally 
sufficient  controlling  force  upon  the  individual.  For  ritual  ob- 
ligations conformity  and  rationalisation  are  provided  by  the  ritual 
sanctions.  The  simplest  form  of  ritual  sanction  is  an  accepted 
belief  that  if  rules  of  ritual  are  not  observed  some  undefined 
misfortune  is  likely  to  occur.  In  many  societies  the  expected 
danger  is  somewhat  more  definitely  conceived  as  a  danger  of 
sickness  or,  in  extreme  cases,  death.  In  the  more  specialised  forms 
of  ritual  sanction  the  good  results  to  be  hoped  for  or  the  bad 
results  to  be  feared  are  more  spectfically  defined  in  reference  to 
the  occasion  or  meaning  of  the  ritual./ 

The  theory  is  not  concerned  with  the  historical  origin  of 
ritual,  nor  is  it  another  attempt  to  explain  ritual  in  terms  of  human 
psychology;  it  is  a  hypothesis  as  to  the  relation  of  ritual  and 
ritual  values  to  the  essential  constitution  of  human  society,  i.e. 
to  those  invariant  general  characters  which  belong  to  all  human 
societies,  past,  present  and  future.  It  rests  on  the  recognition  of 
the  fact  that  while  in  animal  societies  social  coaptation  depends  on 
instinct,Jn^human  societies  it  depends  upon  the  efficacy  of  symbols 
of  many  different  kinds.  The  theory  I  am  advancing  must  there- 
fore, for  a  just  estimation  of  its  value,  be  considered  in  its  place 
in  a  general  theory  of  symbols  and  their  social  efficacy. 

By  this  theory  the  Andamanese  taboos  relating  to  childbirth 
are  the  obligatory  recognition  in  a  standardised  symbolic  form 


TABOO  151 

of  the  significance  and  importance  of  the  event  to  the  parents  and 
to  the  community  at  large.  They  thus  serve  to  fix  the  social  value 
of  occasions  of  this  kind.  Similarly  I  have  argued  in  another  place 
that  the  Andamanese  taboos  relating  to  the  animals  and  plants 
used  for  food  are  means  of  affixing  a  definite  social  value  to  food, 
based  on  its  social  importance.  The  social  importance  of  food  is 
not  that  it  satisfies  hunger,  but  that  in  such  a  community  as  an 
Andamanese  camp  or  village  an  enormously  large  proportion 
of  the  activities  are  concerned  with  the  getting  and  consuming  of 
food,  and  that  in  these  activities,  with  their  daily  instances  of 
collaboration  and  mutual  aid,  there  continuously  occur  those 
inter-relations  of  interests  which  bind  the  individual  men,  women 
and  children  into  a  society. 

I  believe  that  this  theory  can  be  generalised  and  with  suitable 
modifications  wuU  be  found  to  apply  to  a  vast  number  of  the  taboos 
of  different  societies.  My  theory  would  go  further  for  I  would  hold, 
as  a  reasonable  working  hypothesis,  that  we  have  here  the  primary 
basis  of  all  ritual  and  therefore  of  religion  and  magic,  however 
those  may  be  distinguished.  The  primary  basis  of  ritual,  so  the 
formulation  would  run,  is  the  attribution  of  ritual  value  to  objects 
and  occasions  which  are  either  themselves  objects  of  important 
common  interests  linking  together  the  persons  of  a  community 
or  are  symbolically  representative  of  such  objects.  To  illustrate 
what  is  meant  by  the  last  part  of  this  statement  two  illustrations 
may  be  off^ered.  In  the  Andamans  ritual  value  is  attributed  to  the 
cicada,  not  because  it  has  any  social  importance  itself  but  because 
it  symbolically  represents  the  seasons  of  the  year  which  do  have 
importance.  In  some  tribes  of  Eastern  Australia  the  god  Baiame 
is  the  personification,  i.e.  the  symbolical  representative,  of  the 
moral  law  of  the  tribe,  and  the  rainbow-serpent  (the  Australian 
equivalent  of  the  Chinese  dragon)  is  a  symbol  representing 
growth  and  fertility  in  nature.  Baiame  and  the  rainbow-serpent 
in  their  turn  are  represented  by  the  figures  of  earth  which  are 
made  on  the  sacred  ceremonial  ground  of  the  initiation  cere- 
monies and  at  which  rites  are  performed.  The  reverence  that  the 
Australian  shows  to  the  image  of  Baiame  or  towards  his  name  is 
the  symbolic  method  of  fixing  the  social  value  of  the  moral  law, 
particularly  the  laws  relating  to  marriage. 

In  conclusion  let  me  return  once  more  to  the  work  of  the 
anthropologist  whom  we  are  here  to  honour.  Sir  James  Frazer,  in 


152  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

his  Psyche's  Task  and  in  his  other  works,  set  himself  to  show  how, 
in  his  own  words,  taboos  have  contributed  to  build  up  the  complex 
fabric  of  society.  He  thus  initiated  that  functional  study  of  ritual 
to  which  I  have  in  this  lecture  and  elsewhere  attempted  to  make 
some  contribution.  But  there  has  been  a  shift  of  emphasis.  Sir 
James  accounted  for  the  taboos  of  savage  tribes  as  the  application 
in  practice  of  beliefs  arrived  at  by  erroneous  processes  of  reasoning, 
and  he  seems  to  have  thought  of  the  effects  of  these  beliefs  in 
creating  or  maintaining  a  stable  orderly  society  as  being  accidental. 
My  own  view  is  that  the  negative  and  positive  rites  of  savages 
exist  and  persist  because  they  are  part  of  the  mechanism  by  which 
an  orderly  society  maintains  itself  in  existence,  serving  as  they  do 
to  establish  certain  fundamental  social  values.  The  beliefs  by 
which  the  rites  themselves  are  justified  and  given  some  sort  of 
consistency  are  the  rationalisations  of  symbolic  actions  and  of  the 
sentiments  associated  with  them.  I  would  suggest  that  what  Sir 
James  Frazer  seems  to  regard  as  the  accidental  results  of  magical 
and  religious  beliefs  really  constitute  their  essential  function  and 
the  ultimate  reason  for  their  existence. 

NOTE 

The  theory  of  ritual  outlined  in  this  lecture  was  first  worked 
out  in  1908  in  a  thesis  on  the  Andaman  Islanders.  It  was  written 
out  again  in  a  revised  and  extended  form  in  191 3  and  appeared 
in  print  in  1922.  Unfortunately  the  exposition  contained  in 
The  Andaman  Islanders  is  evidently  not  clear,  since  some  of  my 
critics  have  failed  to  understand  what  the  theory  is.  For  example, 
it  has  been  assumed  that  by  'social  value'  I  mean  'utility'. 

The  best  treatment  of  the  subject  of  value  with  which  I  am 
acquainted  is  Ralph  Barton  Perry's  General  Theory  of  Value,  1926. 
For  the  Chinese  theory  of  ritual  the  most  easily  accessible  account 
is  in  chapter  xiv  of  Fung  Yu-lan's  History  of  Chinese  Philosophy, 
1937.  The  third  chapter,  on  the  uses  of  symboHsm,  of  Whitehead's 
Symbolism,  its  Meaning  and  Effect,  is  an  admirable  brief  introduc- 
tion to  the  sociological  theory  of  symbolism. 

One  very  important  point  that  could  not  be  dealt  with  in  the 
lecture  is  that  indicated  by  Whitehead  in  the  following  sentence — 
'No  account  of  the  uses  of  symbolism  is  complete  without  the 
recognition  that  the  symbolic  elements  in  life  have  a  tendency  to 
run  wild,  like  the  vegetation  in  a  tropical  forest.' 


CHAPTER     VIII 


RELIGION  AND   SOCIETY  ^ 


K  1  IHE  Royal  Anthropological  Institute  has  honoured  me 
I  with  an  invitation  to  deliver  the  Henry  Myers  Lecture 
JL.  on  the  role  of  religion  in  the  development  of  human 
society.  That  is  an  important  and  complex  subject,  about  which 
it  is  not  possible  to  say  very  much  in  a  single  lecture,  but  as  it  is 
hoped  that  this  may  be  only  the  first  of  a  continuing  series  of 
lectures,  in  which  different  lecturers  will  each  offer  some  con- 
tribution, I  think  that  the  most  useful  thing  I  can  do  is  to  indicate 
certain  lines  along  which  I  believe  that  an  enquir}^  into  this 
problem  can  be  profitably  pursued. 

The  usual  way  of  looking  at  religions  is  to  regard  all  of  them, 
or  all  except  one,  as  bodies  of  erroneous  beliefs  and  illusory 
practices.  There  is  no  doubt  that  the  histor}'  of  religions  has  been 
in  great  part  a  history  of  error  and  illusion.  In  all  ages  men  have 
hoped  that  by  the  proper  performance  of  religious  actions  or 
observances  they  would  obtain  some  specific  benefit:  health  and 
long  life,  children  to  carry  on  their  line,  material  well-being, 
success  in  hunting,  rain,  the  growth  of  crops  and  the  multiplica- 
tion of  cattle,  victory  in  war,  admission  of  their  souls  after  death 
to  a  paradise,  or  inversely,  release  by  the  extinction  of  personality 
from  the  round  of  reincarnation.  We  do  not  believe  that  the  rain- 
making  rites  of  savage  tribes  really  produce  rain.  Nor  do  we 
believe  that  the  initiates  of  the  ancient  mysteries  did  actually 
attain  through  their  initiation  an  immortality  denied  to  other  men. 
When  we  regard  the  religions  of  other  peoples,  or  at  least  those 
of  what  are  called  primitive  peoples,  as  systems  of  erroneous  and 
illusor}'^  beliefs,  we  are  confronted  with  the  problem  of  ho\^-  these 
beliefs  came  to  be  formulated  and  accepted.  It  is  to  this  problem 
that  anthropologists  have  given  most  attention.  My  personal 
opinion  is  that  this  method  of  approach,  even  though  it  may  seem 
the  most  direct,  is  not  the  one  most  likely  to  lead  to  a  real  under- 
standing of  the  nature  of  religions. 

^  The  Henry  Myers  Lecture,  1945. 
153 


154  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

There  is  another  way  in  which  we  may  approach  the  study  of 
religions.  We  may  entertain  as  at  least  a  possibility  the  theory  that 
any  religion  is  an  important  or  even  essential  part  of  the  social 
machinery,  as  are  morality  and  law,  part  of  the  complex  system 
by  which  human  beings  are  enabled  to  live  together  in  an  orderly 
arrangement  of  social  relations.  From  this  point  of  view  we  deal 
not  with  the  origins  but  with  the  social  functions  of  religions, 
i.e.  the  contribution  that  they  make  to  the  formation  and  main- 
tenance of  a  social  order.  There  are  many  persons  who  would  say 
that  it  is  only  true  religion  (i.e.  one's  own)  that  can  provide  the 
foundation  of  an  orderly  social  life.  The  hypothesis  we  are  con- 
sidering is  that  the  social  function  of  a  religion  is  independent 
of  its  truth  or  falsity,  that  religions  which  we  think  to  be  erroneous 
or  even  absurd  and  repulsive,  such  as  those  of  some  savage  tribes, 
may  be  important  and  effective  parts  of  the  social  machinery, 
and  that  without  these  'false'  religions  social  evolution  and 
the  development  of  modern  civilisation  would  have  been 
impossible. 

The  hypothesis,  therefore,  is  that  in  what  we  regard  as  false 
religions,  ihough,,  the  performance  of  religious  rites  does  not 
actually  produce  the  effects  that  are  expected  or  hoped  for  b_y  those 
who  perform  or  take  part  in  them,  they  have  other  effects,  some 
at  least  of  which  may  be  socially  valuable. 

How  are  we  to  set  to  work  to  test  this  hypothesis?  It  is  of  no 
use  thinking  in  terms  of  religion  in  general,  in  the  abstract,  and 
society  in  the  abstract.  Nor  is  it  adequate  to  consider  some  one 
religion,  particularly  if  it  is  the  one  in  which  we  have  been  brought 
up  and  about  which  we  are  likely  to  be  prejudiced  one  way  or 
another.  The  only  method  is  the  experimental  method  of  social 
anthropology,  and  that  means  that  we  must  study  in  the  light 
of  our  hypothesis  a  sufficient  number  of  diverse  particular 
religions  or  religious  cults  in  their  relation  to  the  particular 
societies  in  which  they  are  found.  This  is  a  task  not  for  one  person  i 
but  for  a  number.  1 

Anthropologists  and  others  have  discussed  at  length  the  ; 
question  of  the  proper  definition  of  religion.  I  do  not  intend  to 
deal  with  that  controversial  subject  on  this  occasion.  But  there 
are  some  points  that  must  be  considered.  I  shall  assume  that  any 
religion  or  any  religious  cult  normally  involves  certain  ideas  or 
beliefs  on  the  one  hand,  and  on  the  other  certain  observances 


RELIGION   AND   SOCIETY  1 55 

These  observances,  positive  and  negative,  i.e.  actions  and  absten- 
tions, I  shall  speak  of  as  rites. 

In  European  countries,  and  more  particularly  since  the 
Reformation,  religion  has  come  to  be  considered  as  primarily  a 
matter  of  belief.  This  is  itself  a  phenomenon  which  needs  to  be 
explained,  I  think,  in  terms  of  social  development.  We  are  con- 
cerned here  only  with  its  effects  on  the  thinking  of  anthropologists. 
Among  many  of  them  there  is  a  tendency  to  treat  belief  as  primary: 
rites  are  considered  as  the  results  of  beliefs.  They  therefore  con- 
centrate their  attention  on  tr^^ing  to  explain  the  beliefs  by  hypo- 
theses as  to  how  they  may  have  been  formed  and  adopted. 

To  my  mind  this  is  the  product  of  false  psychology.  For 
example,  it  is  sometimes  held  that  funeral  and  mourning  rites 
are  the  result  of  a  belief  in  a  soul  surviving  death.  If  we  must 
talk  in  terms  of  cause  and  effect,  I  would  rather  hold  the  view  that 
the  belief  in  a  surviving  soul  is  not  the  cause  but  the  effect  of  the 
rites.  Actually  the  cause-effect  analysis  is  misleading.  What  really 
happens  is  that  the  rites  and  the  justifying  or  rationalising  beliefs 
develop  together  as  parts,  of  a  coherent  whole^  But  in  this  develop- 
mentit_is  action  or  the  need  of  action  that  controls  or  determines 
belief  rather  than  the  other  way  about.  The  actions  themselves 
are  symbolic  expressions  of  sentiments. 

My  suggestion  is  that  in  attempting  to  understand  a  religion 
it  is  on  the  rites  rather  than  on  the  beliefs  that  we  should  first 
concentrate  our  attention.  Much  the  same  view  is  taken  by  Loisy, 
who  justifies  his  selection  of  sacrificial  rites  as  the  subject  of  his 
analysis  of  religion  by  saying  that  rites  are  in  all  religions  the  most 
stable  aiid_ lasting  element,  and  consequently  that  in  which  we 
can  best  discover  the  spirit  of  ancient  cults.  ^ 

That  great  pioneer  of  the  science  of  religion,  Robertson  Smith, 
took  this  view.  He  ^^  rote  as  follows: 

In  connection  with  every  religion,  whether  ancient  or  modern, 
we  find  on  the  one  hand  certain  behefs,  and  on  the  other  certain  in- 
stitutions, ritual  practices  and  rules  of  conduct.  Our  modem  habit 
is  to  look  at  religion  from  the  side  of  belief  rather  than  that  of  practice; 
for,  down  to  comparatively  recent  times,  almost  the  only  forms  of  religion 
seriously  studied  in  Europe  have  been  those  of  the  various  Christian 
Churches,  and  all  parts  of  Christendom  are  agreed  that  ritual  is  important 

^  'Les  rites  6tant  dans  toutes  les  religions  I'^l^ment  le  plus  consistant  et  le 
plus  durable,  celui,  par  consequent,  ou  se  d^couvre  le  mieux  I'esprit  des  cultes 
anciens.' — Essai  historique  sur  le  Sacrifice,  Paris,  1920,  p.  i. 


156  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

only  in  connection  with  its  interpretation.  Thus  the  study  of  religion  has 
meant  mainly  the  study  of  Christian  beliefs,  and  instruction  in  religion 
has  habitually  begun  with  the  creed,  religious  duties  being  presented 
to  the  learner  as  flowing  from  the  dogmatic  truths  he  is  taught  to  accept. 
All  this  seems  to  us  so  much  a  matter  of  course  that,  when  we  approach 
some  strange  or  antique  religion,  we  naturally  assume  that  here  also 
our  first  business  is  to  search  for  a  creed,  and  find  in  it  the  key  to  ritual 
and  practice.  But  the_anjiqiie  religions^ad  for  the  most  part  no  creed; 
they  consisted  entirely  of  institutions  and  practices.  No  doubt  men  will 
not  habitually  follow  certain  practices  without  attaching  a  meaning  to 
them;  but  as  a  rule  we  find  that  while  the  practice  was  rigorously  fixed, 
the  meaning_attached  to  it  was  extremely  vague,  and  the  same  rite  was 
explained  by  different  people Jn  different  ways,  without  any  question  of 
orthodoxy  or  heterodoxy  arising  in  consequence.  In  ancient  Greece,  for 
example,  certain  things  were  done  at  a  temple,  and  people  were  agreed  that 
it  would  be  impious  not  to  do  them.  But  if  you  asked  why  they  were  done 
you  would  probably  have  had  several  mutually  contradictory  explanations 
from  different  persons,  and  no  one  would  have  thought  it  a  matter  of  the 
least  religious  importance  which  of  these  you  chose  to  adopt.  Indeed,  the 
explanations  offered  would  not  have  been  of  a  kind  to  stir  any  strong  feel- 
ing; for  in  most  cases  they  would  have  been  merely  different  stories  as  to 
the  circumstances  under  which  the  rite  first  came  to  be  established,  by  the 
command  or  by  the  direct  example  of  the  god.  The  rite,  in  short,  was 
connected  not  with  dogma  but  with  a  myth.^ 

...  It  is  of  the  first  importance  to  realise  clearly  from  the  outset 
that  ritual  and  practical  usage  were,  strictly  speaking,  the  sum-total  of 
ancient  religions.  Religion  in  primitive  times  was  not  a  system  of  belief 
with  practical  applications;  it  was  a  body  of  fixed  traditional  practices 
to  which  every  member  of  society  conformed  as  a  matter  of  course.  Men 
would  not  be  men  if  they  agreed  to  do  certain  things  without  having  a 
reason  for  their  action;  but  in  ancient  religion  the  reason  was  not  first 
formulated  as  a  doctrine  and  then  expressed  in  practice,  but  conversely, 
practice  preceded  doctrinal  theory.  Men  form  general  rules  of  conduct 
before  they  begin  to  express  general  principles  in  words;  political  in- 
stitutions are  older  than  political  theories,  and  in  like  manner  religious 
institutions  are  older  than  religious  theories.  This  analogy  is  not  ar- 
bitrarily chosen,  for  in  fact  the  parallelism  in  ancient  society  between 
religious  and  political  institutions  is  complete.  In  each  sphere  great 
importance  was  attached  to  form  and  precedent,  but  the  explanation 
why  the  precedent  was  followed  consisted  merely  of  a  legend  as  to  its 
first  establisliment.  That  the  precedent,  once  established,  was  authoritative 
did  not  appear  to  require  any  proof.  The  rules  of  society  were  based  on 
precedent,  and  the  continued  existence  of  the  society  was  sufficient 
reason  why  a  precedent  once  set  should  continue  to  be  followed.* 

^  W.  Robertson  Smith,  Lectures  on  the  Religion  of  the  Semites,  1907,  pp.  16-17. 
*  op.  cit.,  p.  20. 


RELIGION   AND   SOCIETY  1 57 

The  relative  stability  of  rites  and  the  variability  of  doctrines 
can  be  illustrated  from  the  Christian  religions.  The  two  essential 
rites  of  all  Christian  religions  are  baptism  and  the  eucharist,  and 
we  know  that  the  latter  solemn  sacrament  is  interpreted  differently 
in  the  Orthodox  Church,  the  Roman  Church  and  the  Anglican 
Church.  The  modern  emphasis  on  the  exact  formulation  of 
beliefs  connected  with  the  rites  rather  than  on  the  rites  themselves 
is  demonstrated  in  the  way  in  w^hich  Christians  have  fought  with 
and  killed  one  another  over  differences  of  doctrine. 

Thirty-seven  years  ago  (1908),  in  a  fellowship  thesis  on  the 
Andaman  Islanders  (which  did  not  appear  in  print  till  1922), 
I  formulated  briefly  a  general  theory  of  the  social  function  of  rites 
and  ceremonies.  It  is  the  same  theory  that  underlies  the  remarks  I 
shall  offer  on  this  occasion.  Stated  in  the  simplest  possible  terms 
the  theory  is  that  an  orderly  social  life  amongst  human  beings 
depends  upon  the  presence  in  the  minds  of  the  members  of  a 
society  of  certain  sentiments,  which  control  the  behaviour  of  the 
individual  in  his  relation  to  others.  Rites  can  be  seen  to  be  the 
regulated  symbolic  expressions  of  certain  sentiments.  Rites  cart 
therefore  be  shown  to  have  a  specific  social  function  when,  and 
to  the  extent  that,  they  have  for  their  effect  to  regulate,  maintain 
and  transmit  from  one  generation  to  another  sentiments  on  which 
the  constitution  of  the  society  depends.  I  ventured  to  suggest  as  a 
general  formula  that  religionjs.Xia:ywJiejre_an  expression  in  one 
form  or  anQther_Df__^a  sense  of  dependence^on  a  powder  outside 
ourselYes,^^-^Gwer_:which~\ve^rhay  speajc^of  as  a  spiritual  or  moralj 
power. 

This  theory  is  by  no  means  new.  It  is  to  be  found  in  the  writings 
of  the  philosophers  of  ancient  China.  It  is  most  explicit  in  the 
teachings  of  Hsiin  TziQ  who  lived  in  the  third  century'  B.C.,  and 
in  the  Book  of  Rites  (the  Li  Chi),  which  was  compiled  some  time 
later.  The  Chinese  wTiters  do  not  write  about  religion.  I  am  doubt- 
ful if  there  is  in  Chinese  any  w^ord  which  will  convey  just  what 
we  understand  by  the  word  religion.  They  write  about  //',  and  the 
word  is  variously  translated  as  ceremonial,  customary'  moralit}'', 
rites,  rules  of  good  manners,  propriety.  But  the  character  by  which 
this  word  is  written  consists  of  two  parts,  of  which  one  refers 
to  spirits,  sacrifice  and  prayer,  and  the  other  originally  meant  a 
vessel  used  in  performing  sacrifices.  We  may  therefore  appro- 
priately  translate   li  as   'ritual'.   In  any  case   what  the  ancient 


158  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

philosophers  are  chiefly  concerned  with  are  the  rites  of  mourning 
and  sacrificial  rites. 

There  is  no  doubt  that  in  China,  as  elsewhere,  it  \A'as  thought 
that  many  or  all  of  the  religious  rites  were  efficacious  in  the  sense 
of  averting  evils  and  bringing  blessings.  It  was  believed  that  the 
seasons  would  not  follow  one  another  in  due  order  unless  the 
Emperor,  the  Son  of  Heaven,  performed  the  established  rites  at 
the  appropriate  times.  Even  under  the  Republic  a  reluctant  magis- 
trate of  a  hsien  may  be  compelled  by  public  opinion  to  take  the 
leading  part  in  a  ceremony  to  bring  rain.  But  there  developed 
among  the  scholars  an  attitude  which  might  perhaps  be  called 
rationalistic  and  agnostic.  For  the  most  part  the  question  of  the 
efficacy  of  rites  was  not  considered.  What  was  thought  important 
was  the  social  function  of  the  rites,  i.e.  their  effects  in  producing 
and  maintaining  an  orderly  human  society. 

In  a  text  that  is  earlier  than  Confucius  we  read  that  'sacrifice 
is  that  through  which  one  can  show  one's  filial  piety  and  give 
peace  to  the  people,  pacify  the  country  and  make  the  people 
settled.  ...  It  is  through  the  sacrifices  that  the  unity  of  the 
people  is  strengthened'  {CKu  Yii,  II,  2). 

You  know  that  one  of  the  major  points  of  the  teaching  of 
Confucius  was  the  importance  of  the  proper  performance  of  rites. 
But  it  is  said  of  Confucius  that  he  would  not  discuss  the  super- 
natural. ^  In  the  Confucian  philosophy,  music  and  ritual  are  con- 
sidered as  means  for  the  establishment  and  preservation  of  social 
order,  and  regarded  as  superior  to  laws  and  punishments  as  means 
to  this  end.  We  take  a  very  different  view  of  music,  but  I  may 
remind  you  that  Plato  held  somewhat  similar  ideas,  and  I  suggest 
that  an  anthropological  study  of  the  relations  between  music  (and 
dancing)  and  religious  rituals  would  provide  some  interesting 
results.  In  the  Book  of  Rites  one  section  (the  Yiieh  Chi)  is  con- 
cerned with  music.  The  third  paragraph  reads: 

The  ancient  kings  were  watchful  in  regard  to  the  things  by  which  the 
mind  was  affected.  And  so  they  instituted  ceremonies  to  direct  men's 
aims  aright;  music  to  give  harmony  to  their  voices;  laws  to  unify  their 
conduct;  and  punishments  to  guard  against  their  tendencies  to  evil. 
The  end  to  which  ceremonies,  music,  punishments  and  laws  conduct 

^  Analects,  VII,  20.  Waley  translates  this  passage  as:  'The  Master  never 
talked  of  prodigies,  feats  of  strength,  disorders  or  spirits.' 


RELIGION   AND   SOCIETY  1 59 

is  one;  they  are  the  instruments  by  which  the  minds  of  the  people  are 
assimilated,  and  good  order  in  government  is  made  to  appear.  ^ 

The  view  of  religion  that  we  are  here  concerned  with  might 
be  summed  up  in  the  following  sentence  from  the  Book  of  Rites, 
'Ceremonies  are  the  bond  that  holds  the  multitudes  together,  and 
if  the  bond  be  removed,  those  multitudes  fall  into  confusion.' 

The  later  Confucian  philosophers,  beginning  with  Hsiin 
Tzu,  paid  attention  to  the  ways  in  which  rites,  particularly  the 
mourning  and  sacrificial  rites,  performed  their  function  of  main- 
taining social  order.  The  chief  point  of  their  theory  is  that  the  rites 
serve  to  'regulate'  and  'refine'  human  feelings.  Hsiin  Tzii  says: 

Sacrificial  rites  are  the  expressions  of  man's  aflfectionate  longings. 
They  represent  the  height  of  altruism,  faithfulness,  love  and  reverence. 
They  represent  the  completion  of  propriety  and  refinement.  ^ 

Of  the  mourning  rites  Hsiin  Tzu  says: 

The  rites  (li)  consist  in  being  careful  about  the  treatment  of  life  and 
death.  Life  is  the  beginning  of  man,  Death  is  the  end  of  man.  When 
the  end  and  begirming  are  both  good,  the  way  of  humanity  is  complete. 
Hence  the  Superior  Man  respects  the  beginning  and  venerates  the  end. 
To  make  the  end  and  beginning  uniform  is  the  practice  of  the  Superior 
man,  and  is  that  in  which  lies  the  beauty  of  li  and  standards  of  justice  (0- 
For  to  pay  over-attention  to  the  living  and  belittle  the  dead  would  be  to 
respect  them  when  they  have  knowledge  and  disrespect  them  when  they 
have  not.  .  .  . 

The  way  of  death  is  this:  once  dead,  a  person  cannot  return  again. 
[It  is  in  realising  this  that]  the  minister  most  completely  fulfils  the  honour 
due  to  his  ruler,  and  the  son  the  honour  of  his  parents. 

Funeral  rites  are  for  the  living  to  give  beautified  ceremonial  to  the 
dead;  to  send  off  the  dead  as  if  they  were  living;  to  render  the  same  service 
to  the  dead  as  to  the  living;  to  the  absent  as  to  the  present;  and  to  make 
the  end  be  the  same  as  the  beginning.  .  . 

Articles  used  in  life  are  prepared  so  as  to  be  put  into  the  grave,  as  if 
[the  deceased]  were  only  moving  house.  Only  a  few  things  are  taken, 
not  all  of  them.  They  are  to  give  the  appearance,  but  are  not  for  prac- 
tical use.  .  .  .  Hence  the  things  [such  as  were  used]  in  life  are  adorned, 
but  not  completed,  and  the  'spiritual  utensils'  are  for  appearance  but 
not  use.  .  .  .^ 

^  Legge's  translation.  An  alternative  translation  of  the  last  sentence  would 
be:  'Rites,  music,  punishments,  laws  have  one  and  the  same  end,  to  unite 
hearts  and  establish  order.' 

^  The  translations  from  Hsiin  Tzu  are  those  of  Fung  Yu  Lan  and  are  quoted 
from  his  History  of  Chinese  Philosophy,  Peiping,  1937. 

^  Fung  Yu  Lan  translates  by  the  term  'spiritual  utensils'  the  Chinese  ming 
ch'i,  which  Legge  in  the  following  passage  from  the  Book  of  Rites  translates  as 


l6o  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

Hence  the  funeral  rites  are  for  no  other  purpose  than  to  make  clear 
the  meaning  of  death  and  life,  to  send  off  the  dead  with  sorrow  and 
reverence,  and  when  the  end  comes,  to  prepare  for  storing  the  body 
away.  .  .  .  Service  to  the  living  is  beautifying  their  beginning;  sending 
off  the  dead  is  beautifying  their  end.  When  the  end  and  the  beginning 
are  both  attended  to,  the  service  of  the  filial  son  is  ended  and  the  way  of 
the  Sage  is  completed.  Slighting  the  dead  and  over-emphasising  the 
living  is  the  way  of  Mo  (Tzfi).^  Shghting  the  living  and  over-attention 
to-the-  dead  is  the  way  of  superstitionT^KiTIing  the  living  to  send  off  the 
dead  is  murder.^  The  method  and  manner  of  li  and  standards  of  justice  (i) 
is  to  send  off  the  dead  as  if  they  were  alive,  so  that  in  death  and  life,  the 
end  and  the  beginning,  there  is  nothing  that  is  not  appropriate  and  good. 
The  Confucian  does  this. 

The  view  taken  by  this  school  of  ancient  philosophers  was 
that  ^rehgious  rites  have  important  social  functions  which  are 
independent  of  any  behefs  that  may  be  held  as  to  the  efficacy 
of  the  rites.  The  rites  gave  regulated  expression  to  certain  human 
feelings  and  sentiments  and  so  kept  these  sentiments  alive  and 
active.  In  turn  it  was  these  sentiments  which,  by  their  control 
of  or  influence  on  the  conduct  of  individuals,  made  possible  the 
existence  and  continuance  of  an  orderly  social  life.'^ 

It  is  this  theory  that  I  propose  for  your  consideration.  Applied, 
not  to  a  single  society  such  as  ancient  China,  but  to  all  human 
societies,  it  points  to  the  correlation  and  co-variation  of  difl"erent 
characteristics  or  elements  of  social  system4!.Societies  differ  from 
one  another  in  their  structure  and  constitution  and  therefore 
in  the  customary  rules  of  behaviour  of  persons  one  to  another. 
The  system  of  sentiments  on  which  the  social  constitution  depends 
must  therefore  vary  in  correspondence  with  the  difference  of 
constitution.  In  so  far  as  religion  has  the  kind  of  social  function 

'vessels  to  the  eye  of  fancy':  'Confucius  said,  "In  dealing  with  the  dead,  if  we 
treat  them  as  if  they  were  entirely  dead,  that  would  show  a  want  of  affection, 
and  should  not  be  done;  or,  if  we  treat  them  as  if  they  were  entirely  alive, 
that  would  show  a  want  of  wisdom,  and  should  not  be  done.  On  this  account 
the  vessels  of  bamboo  [used  in  connection  with  the  burial  of  the  dead]  are  not 
fit  for  actual  use;  those  of  earthenware  cannot  be  used  to  wash  in;  those  of  wood 
are  incapable  of  being  carved;  the  lutes  are  strung,  but  not  evenly;  the  pandean 
pipes  are  complete,  but  not  in  tune;  the  bells  and  musical  stones  are  there, 
but  they  have  no  stands.  They  are  called  vessels  to  the  eye  of  fancy;  that  is 
[the  dead]  are  thus  treated  as  if  they  were  spiritual  intelligencies."  '  Legge, 
The  Sacred  Books  of  China,  Part  III,  The  Li  Ki,  I-X,  Oxford,  1885,  p.  148. 

^  Mo  Tzu  was  a  philosopher  who  criticised  the  mourning  rites  as  being 
wasteful. 

*  Referring  to  the  ancient  practice  of  human  sacrifice  at  the  burial  of  im- 
portant persons. 


RELIGION   AND   SOCIETY  l6l 

that  the  theory  suggests,  relmmn  piust  also  yar^Mn^coiresponjenr.e 
with  the  manner  in  which  the  society  is  constituted.  In  a  social 
system  constituted  on  the  basis  of  nations  which  make  war  on  one 
another,  or  stand  ready  to  do  so,  a  well-developed  sentiment  of 
patriotism  in  its  members  is  essential  to  maintain  a  strong  nation. 
In  such  circumstances  patriotism  or  national  feeling  may  be 
given  support  by  religion.  Thus  the  Children  of  Israel,  when  they 
invaded  the  land  of  Canaan  under  the  leadership  of  Joshua,  were 
inspired  by  the  religion  that  had  been  taught  to  them  by  Moses 
and  was  centred  upon  the  Holy  Tabernacle  and  its  rites. 

War  or  the  envisaged  possibility  of  war  is  an  essential  element 
in  the  constitution  of  great  numbers  of  human  societies,  though 
the  warlike  spirit  varies  very  much  from  one  to  another.  It  is 
thus  in  accordance  with  our  theory  that  one  of  the  social  functions 
of  religion  is  in  connection  with  war.  Jt  can  give  men  faith  and 
confidence  and  devotion  when  they  go  out  to  do  battle,  whether 
they  are  the  aggressors  or  are  resisting  aggression.  In  the  recent 
conflict  the  German  people  seem  to  have  prayed  to  God  for 
victory  not  less  fervently  than  the  people  of  the  allied  nations. 

It  will  be  evident  that  to  test  our  theor}'  we  must  examine  many 
societies  to  see  if  there  is  a  demonstrable  correspondence  of  the 
religion  or  religions  of  any  one  of  them  and  the  manner  in  which 
that  society  is  constituted.  If  such  a  correspondence  can  be  made 
out,  w^e  must  then  try  to  discover  and  as  far  as  possible  define 
the  major  sentiments  that  find  their  expression  in  the  religion 
and  at  the  same  time  contribute  to  the  maintenance  of  stability 
in  the  society  as  constituted. 

An  important  contribution  to  our  study  is  to  be  found  in  a 
book  that  is  undeservedly  neglected  by  anthropologists,  La  Citi 
antique,  by  the  historian  Fustel  de  Coulanges.  It  is  true  that  it 
was  written  some  time  ago  (1864)  and  that  in  some  matters  it 
may  need  correction  in  the  fight  of  later  historical  research,  but 
it  remains  a  valuable  contribution  to  the  theory  of  the  social 
function  of  religion. 

The  purpose  of  the  book  is  to  show  the  point-by-point 
correspondence  between  religion  and  the  constitution  of  society 
in  ancient  Greece  and  Rome,  and  how  in  the  course  of  history 
the  two  changed  together.  It  is  true  that  the  author,  in  conformity 
with  the  ideas  of  the  nineteenth  century,  conceived  this  cor- 
relation between  two  sets  of  social  features  in  terms  of  cause  and 
6 


1 62  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

effect,  those  of  one  set  being  thought  of  as  the  cause  producing  those 
of  the  other  set.  The  men  of  the  ancient  world,  so  the  argument 
runs,  came  to  hold  certain  beliefs  about  the  souls  of  the  dead. 
As  the  result  of  their  beliefs  they  made  offerings  at  their  tombs. 

Since  the  dead  had  need  of  food  and  drink  it  appeared  to  be  a  duty 
of  the  living  to  satisfy  this  need.  The  care  of  supplying  the  dead  with 
sustenance  was  not  left  to  the  caprice  or  to  the  variable  sentiments  of 
of  men;  it  was  obligatory.  Thus  a  complete  religion  of  the  dead  was 
established,  whose  dogmas  might  soon  be  effaced,  but  whose  rites 
endured  until  the  triumph  of  Christianity.  ^ 

It  was  a  result  of  this  religion  that  ancient  society  came  to  be 
constituted  on  the  basis  of  the  family,  the  agnatic  lineage  and  the 
gens,  with  its  laws  of  succession,  property,  authority  and  marriage. 

A  comparison  of  beliefs  and  laws  shows  that  a  primitive  religion 
constituted  the  Greek  and  Roman  family,  established  marriage  and 
paternal  authority,  fixed  the  order  of  relationship,  and  consecrated  the 
right  of  property  and  the  right  of  inheritance.  This  same  religion,  after 
having  enlarged  and  extended  the  family,  formed  a  still  larger  association, 
the  city,  and  reigned  in  that  as  it  had  reigned  in  the  family.  From  it  came 
all  the  institutions,  as  well  as  all  the  private  law,  of  the  ancients.  It  was 
from  this  that  the  city  received  all  its  principles,  its  rules,  its  usages  and 
its  magistracies.  But,  in  the  course  of  time,  this  ancient  religion  became 
modified  or  effaced,  and  private  law  and  political  institutions  were  modi- 
fied with  it.  Then  came  a  series  of  revolutions,  and  social  changes 
regularly  followed  the  development  of  knowledge.^ 

In  his  final  paragraph  the  author  writes: 

We  have  written  the  history  of  a  belief.  It  was  established  and  human 
society  was  constituted.  It  was  modified,  and  society  underwent  a  series 
of  revolutions.  It  disappeared  and  society  changed  its  character.^ 

This  idea  of  the  primacy  of  belief  and  of  a  causal  relation  in 
which  the  religion  is  the  cause  and  the  other  institutions  are  the 
effect  is  in  accordance  with  a  mode  of  thought  that  was  conmion 
in  the  nineteenth  century.  We  can,  as  I  indeed  do,  completely 
reject  this  theory  and  yet  retain  as  a  valuable  and  permanent 
contribution  to  our  subject  a  great  deal  of  what  Fustel  de  Coulanges 
wrote.  We  can  say  that  he  has  produced  evidence  that  in  ancient 
Greece  and  Rome  the  religion  on  the  one  side  and  the  many 
important  institutions  on  the  other  are  closely  united  as  inter- 

^  The  Ancient  City  (trans.  Willard  Small),  p.  23. 
^  op  cit.,  p.  12.  ^  op  cit.,  p.  529. 


RELIGION  AND   SOCIETY  1 63 

dependent  parts  of  a  coherent  and  unified  system.  The  rehgion 
was  an  essential  part  of  the  constitution  of  the  society.  The  form  of 
the  rehgion  and  the  form  of  the  social  structure  correspond  one 
with  the  other.  We  cannot,  as  Fustel  de  Coulanges  says,  under- 
stand the  social,  juridical  and  political  institutions  of  the  ancient 
societies  unless  we  take  the  religion  into  account.  But  it  is  equally 
true  that  we  cannot  understand  the  religion  except  by  an  examina- 
tion of  its  relation  to  the  institutions. 

A  most  important  part  of  the  religion  of  ancient  Greece  and 
Rome  was  the  worship  of  ancestors.  We  may  regard  this  as  one 
instance  of  a  certain  type  of  religion.  A  religious  cult  of  the  same 
general  kind  has  existed  in  China  from  ancient  times  to  the  present 
day.  Cults  of  the  same  kind  exist  to-day  and  can  be  studied  in 
many  parts  of  Africa  and  Asia.  It  is  therefore  possible  to  make  a 
wide  comparative  study  of  this  type  of  religion.  In  my  own  ex- 
perience it  is  in  ancestor- worship  that  we  can  most  easily  discover 
and  demonstrate  the  social  function  of  a  religious  cult. 

The  term  'ancestor- worship'  is  sometimes  used  in  a  wide, 
loose  sense  to  refer  to  any  sort  of  rites  referring  to  dead  persons. 
I  propose  to  use  it  in  a  more  limited  and  more  precisely  defined 
sense.  The  cult  group  in  this  religion  consists  solely  of  persons 
related  to  one  another  by  descent  in  one  line  from  the  same 
ancestor  or  ancestors.  In  most  instances  descent  is  patrilineal, 
through  males.  But  in  some  societies,  such  as  the  Bakongo  in 
Africa  and  the  Nayar  in  India,  descent  is  matrilineal,  and  the 
cult  group  consists  of  descendants  of  a  single  ancestress.  The  rites 
in  which  the  members  of  the  group,  and  only  they,  participate 
have  reference  to  their  own  ancestors,  and  normally  they  include 
the  making  of  offerings  or  sacrifices  to  them. 

A  particular  lineage  consists  of  three  or  more  generations. 
A  lineage  of  four  or  five  generations  will  normally  be  included  as  a 
part  in  one  of  six  or  seven  generations.  In  a  well-developed  system 
related  lineages  are  united  into  a  larger  body,  such  as  the  Roman 
gens,  or  what  may  be  called  the  clan  in  China.  In  parts  of  China 
we  can  find  a  large  body  of  persons,  numbering  in  some  instances 
as  much  as  a  thousand,  all  having  the  same  name  and  tracing  their 
descent  in  the  male  line  from  a  single  ancestor,  the  founder  of 
the  clan.  The  clan  itself  is  divided  into  lineages. 

A  lineage,  if  it  is  of  more  than  tliree  or  four  generations, 
includes  both  living  persons  and  dead  persons.  What  is  called 


164  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

ancestor-worship  consists  of  rites  carried  out  by  members  of  a 
larger  or  smaller  lineage  (i.e.  one  consisting  of  more  or  fewer 
generations)  with  reference  to  the  deceased  members  of  the 
lineage.  Such  rites  include  the  making  of  offerings,  usually  of 
food  and  drink,  and  such  offerings  are  sometimes  interpreted  as 
the  sharing  of  a  meal  by  the  dead  and  the  living. 

In  such  a  society,  what  gives  stability  to  the  social  structure 
is  the  solidarity  and  continuity  of  the  hneage,  and  of  the  wider 
group  (the  clan)  composed  of  related  lineages.  For  the  individual, 
his  primary  duties  are  those  to  his  lineage.  These  include  duties 
to  the  members  now  living,  but  also  to  those  who  have  died  and  to 
those  who  are  not  yet  born.  In  the  carrying  out  of  these  duties 
he  is  controlled  and  inspired  by  the  complex  system  of  sentiments 
of  which  we  may  say  that  the  object  on  which  they  are  centred 
is  the  lineage  itself,  past,  present  and  future.  It  is  primarily  this 
system  of  sentiments  that  is  expressed  in  the  rites  of  the  cult  of  the 
ancestors.  The  social  fujiction  of  the  rites  is  obvious:  by  giving 
solemn  and  collective  expression  to  them  the  rites  reaffirm,  renew 
and  strengthen  those  sentiments  on  which  the  social  solidarity 
depends. 

We  have  no  means  of  studying  how  an  ancestor-worshipping 
society  comes  into  existence,  but  we  can  study  the  decay  of  this 
type  of  system  in  the  past  and  in  the  present.  Fustel  de  Coulanges 
deals  with  this  in  ancient  Greece  and  Rome.  It  can  be  observed 
at  the  present  time  in  various  parts  of  the  world.  The  scanty 
information  I  have  been  able  to  gather  suggests  that  the  lineage 
and  joint-family  organisation  of  some  parts  of  India  is  losing 
something  of  its  former  strength  and  solidarity  and  that  what  we 
should  expect  as  the  inevitable  accompaniment  of  this,  a  weaken- 
ing of  the  cult  of  ancestors,  is  also  taking  place.  I  can  speak  with 
more  assurance  about  some  African  societies,  particularly  those 
of  South  Africa.  The  effect  of  the  impact  of  European  culture, 
including  the  teaching  of  the  Christian  missionaries,  is  to  weaken 
in  some  individuals  the  sentiments  that  attach  them  to  their 
lineage.  The  disintegration  of  the  social  structure  and  the  decay 
of  the  ancestral  cult  proceed  together. 

Thus  for  one  particular  type  of  religion  I  am  ready  to  affirm 
that  the  general  theory  of  the  social  function  of  religions  can  be 
fully  demonstrated. 

A  most  important  contribution  to  our  subject  is  a  work  of 


RELIGION   AND   SOCIETY  165 

Emile  Durkheim  published  in  1912.  The  title  is  Les  Formes 
elementaires  de  la  Vie  religieuse,  but  the  sub-title  reads:  La  Systeme 
totemique  en  Australie.  It  is  worth  while  mentioning  that  Durkheim 
was  a  pupil  of  FusteLde  Coulanges  at  the  Ecole  Normale  Superieure 
and  that  he  himself  said  that  the  most  important  influence  on  the 
development  of  his  ideas  about  religion  was  that  of  Robertson 
Smith. 

Durkheim's  aim  was  to  establish  a  general  theory  of  the  nature 
of  religion.  Instead  of  a  wide  comparative  study  of  many  religions, 
he  preferred  to  take  a  simple  type  of  society  and  carry  out  an  in- 
tensive and  detailed  analysis,  and  for  this  purpose  he  selected  the 
aboriginal  tribes^of_Australia.  He  held  the  view  that  these  tribes 
represent  the  simplest  type  of  society  surviving  to  our  own  times, 
but  the  value  of  his  analysis^tSTTTTTorWay  affected  if  we  refuse  to 
accept  this  view,  as  I  do  myself. 

The  value  of  Durkheim's  book  is  as  an  exposition  of  a  general 
theory  of  religion  which  had  been  developed  with  the  collabora- 
tion of  Henri  Hubert  and  Marcel  Mauss,  starting  from  the  founda- 
tions provided  by  Robertson  Smith.  Durkheim's  exposition  of  this 
theory  has  often  been  very  much  misunderstood.  A  clear,  though 
very  brief,  statement  of  it  is  to  be  found  in  the  Introduction 
written  by  Henri  Hubert  in  1904  for  the  French  translation  of  the 
Manuel  d'Histoire  des  Religions  of  Chantepie  de  la  Saussaye. 
But  it  is  not  possible  on  this  occasion  to  discuss  this  general 
theory.  I  wish  only  to  deal  with  one  part  of  Durkheim's  work, 
namely  his 'theory  that  religious  ritual  is  an  expxsssion  of  the 
unity  of  soaej^Tand  that  its  function  is  to  're-create'  the  society 
of  the  social  order  by  reaffirming  and  strengthening  the  senti- 
ments on  which  the  social  solidarity  and  therefore  the  social  order 
itself  depend.^  This  theory  he  tests  by  an  examination  of  the 
totemic  ritual  of  the  Australians.  For  while  Frazer  regarded  the 
totemic  rites  of  the  Australian  tribes  as  being  a  matter  of  magic, 
Durkheim  treats  them  as  religious  because  the  rites  themselves 
are  sacred  and  have  reference  to  sacred  beings,  sacred  places  and 
sacred  objects. 

In  191 2  very  much  less  was  known  about  the  Australian 
aborigines  than  is  known  at  present.  Some  of  the  sources  used 
by  Durkheim  have  proved  to  be  unreliable.  The  one  tribe  that 
was  well  known,  through  the  writings  of  Spencer  and  Gillen  and 

^  op  cit.,  pp.  323,  497  and  elsewhere. 


1 66  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

Strehlow — the  Aranda — is  in  some  respects  atypical.  The  in- 
formation that  Durkheim  could  use  was  therefore  decidedly 
imperfect.  Moreover,  it  cannot  be  said  that  his  handling  of  this 
material  was  all  that  it  might  have  been.  Consequently  there  are 
many  points  in  his  exposition  wliich  I  find  unacceptable.  Never- 
theless, I  think  that  Durkheim's  major  thesis  as  to  the  social 
function  of  the  totemic  rites  is  valid  and  only  requires  revision 
and  correction  in  the  light  of  the  more  extensive  and  more  exact 
knowledge  we  now  have.^ 

The  beings  to  which  the  Australian  cult  refers  are  commonly 
spoken  of  as  'totemic  ancestors',  and  I  have  myself  used  the  term. 
But  it  is  somewhat  misleading,  since  thej_arejnythical  beings  and ' 
not  ac.cest.9rs  in  the  same  sense  as  the  dead  persons  conmiemorated 
in  ancestor-worship.  In  the  cosmology  of  the  Australian  natives 
the  cosmos,  the  ordered  universe,  including  both  the  order  of 
nature  and  the  social  order,  came  into  existence  at  a  time  in  the 
past  which  I  propose  to  speak  of  as  the  World- Dawn,  for  this 
name  corresponds  to  certain  ideas  that  I  have  found  amongst  the 
aborigines  of  some  tribes.  This  order  (of  nature  and  of  society) 
resulted  from  the  doings  and  adventures  of  certain  sacred  beings. 
These  beings,  whom  I  shall  call  the  Dawn  Beings,  are  the  totemic 
ancestors  of  ethnological  literature.  The  explanations  of  topo- 
graphical features,  of  natural  species  and  their  characteristics,  and 
of  social  laws,  customs  and  usages  are  given  in  the  form  of  myths 
about  the  happenings  of  the  World- Dawn. 

The  cosmos  is  ruled  by  law.  But  whereas  we  think  of  the 
laws  of  nature  as  statements  of  what  invariably  does  happen 
(except,  of  course,  in  miracles),  and  of  moral  or  social  laws  as  what 
ought  to  be  observed  but  are  sometimes  broken,  the  Australian 
does  not  make  this  distinction.  For  him  men  and  women  ought  to 
observe  the  rules  of  behaviour  that  were  fixed  for  all  time  by  the 
events  of  the  World- Dawn,  and  similarly  the  rain  ought  to  fall  in 
its  proper  season,  plants  should  grow  and  produce  fruit  or  seed, 
and  animals  should  bear  young.  But  there  are  irregularities  in 
human  society  and  in  nature. 

In  what  I  shall  venture  to  call  the  totemic  religion  of  the 
Australian  aborigines,  there  are  two  main  types  of  ritual.  One  of 
these  consists  of  rites  carried  out  at  certain  spots  which  are  com- 

^  For  a  criticism  of  some  points  in  Durkheim's  work,  see  'The  Sociological 
Theory  of  Totemism'  in  this  volume. 


RELIGION  AND   SOCIETY  1 67 

monly  referred  to  as  'totem  centres'.  A  totem  centre  is  a  spot  that  is 
specially  connected  with  some  species  of  object,  most  commonly 
with  a  particular  species  of  animal  or  plant,  or  with  an  aspect  of 
nature  such  as  rain  or  hot  weather.  Each  centre  is  associated  with 
one  (or  occasionally  more  than  one)  of  the  Dawn  Beings.  Fre- 
quently the  Being  is  said  to  have  gone  into  the  ground  at  this  spot. 
For  each  totem  centre  there  is  a  myth  connecting  it  w  ith  the  events 
of  the  World-Dawn.  The  totem  centre,  the  myth  connected  with  it 
and  the  rites  that  are  performed~there,  belong  to  the  local  group 
that  owns  the  territory  within  which  the  totem  centre  lies.  Each 
totem  centre  is  thought  of  as  containing,  in  a  rock  or  a  tree  or  a 
pool  of  water  or  a  heap  of  stones,  what  we  may  perhaps  call  the 
hfe-spirit  or  life-force  of  the  totem  species. 

The  rites  performed  at  the  totem  centre  by  the  members  of  the 
local  group  to  which  it  belongs,  or  under  their  leadership  and 
direction,  are  thought  tojenew  the  vitality  of  this  life-spirit  of  the 
species.  In  eastern  Australia  theTofem  centre  is  spoken  of  as  the 
'home'  or  'dwelling-place'  of  the  species,  and  the  rites  are  called 
'stirring  up'.  Thus,  the  rite  at  a  rain  totem  centre  brings  the  rain 
in  its  due  season,  that  at  a  kangaroo  totem  centre  ensures  the 
supply  of  kangaroos,  and  that  at  the  baby  totem  centre  provides 
for  the  birth  of  children  in  the  tribe. 

These  rites  imply  a  certain  conception,  which  I  think  we  can 
call  specifically  a  religious  conception,  of  the  place  of  man  in  the 
universe.  Man  is  dependent  upon  what  we  call  nature:  on  the 
regular  successions  of  the  seasons,  on  the  rain  falling  when  it  should, 
on  the  growth  of  plants  and  the  continuance  of  animal  life.  But, 
as  I  have  already  said,  while  for  us  the  order  of  nature  is  one  . 
thing  and  the  social  order  another,  for  the  Australian  they  are  1 
two  parts  of  a  single  order.  Well-being,  for  the  individual  or  ' 
for  the  society,  depends  on  the  continuance  of  this  order  free 
from  serious  disturbance.  The  Australians  believe  that  they  can   \ 
ensure  this  continuance,  or  at  least  contribute  to  it,  by  their  actions, 
including  the  regular  performance  of  the  totemic  rites. 

In  the  rites  that  have  been  described,  each  group  takes  care 
(if  we  may  so  express  it)  of  only  a  small  part  of  nature,  of  those 
few  species  for  which  it  owns  totem  centres.  The  preservation  of 
the  natural  order  as  a  whole  therefore  depends  on  the  actions  of 
many  dirferent  groups. 

The  social  structure  of  the  Australian  natives  is  based  on  two 


1 68  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

things:  a  system  of  local  groups,  and  a  system  of  kinship  based  on 
the  family.  Each  small  local  group  is  a  closed  patrilineal  descent 
group;  that  is,  a  man  is  born  into  the  group  of  his  father  and  his 
sons  belong  to  his  group.  Each  group  is  independent  and  autono- 
mous. The  stability  and  continuity  of  the  social  structure  depends 
on  the  strong  solidarity  of  the  local  group. 

Where  there  existed  the  totemic  cult  which  I  have  just  de- 
scribed (and  it  existed  over  a  very  large  part  of  Australia),  each 
local  group  was  a  cult  group.  The  totemic  ritual  served  to  express 
thejmity^ and  solidarity  of  the  group"  and  its  individuality  and 
separation  from  other  groups  by  the  special  relation  of  the  group 
to  its  sacra:  the  totem  centre  or  centres,  the  Dawn  Beings  associated 
with  them,  the  myths  and  songs  referring  to  those  Beings,  and  the 
totems  or  species  connected  with  the  centres.  This  aspect  of  the 
social  function  of  totemism  was  emphasised,  and  I  think  somewhat 
over-emphasised,  by  Durkheim. 

There  is,  however,  another  aspect,  for  while  the  local  totemic 
groups  are  separate  individual  and  continuing  social  entities,  they 
are  also  part  of  a  wider  social  structure.  This  wider  structure  is 
provided  by  the  kinship  system.  For  an  individual  in  Australian 
native  society,  every  person  with  whom  he  has  any  social  contact 
is  related  to  him  by  some  bond  of  kinship,  near  or  distant,  and 
the  regulation  of  social  life  consists  essentially  of  rules  concerning 
behaviour  towards  different  kinds  of  kin.  For  example,  a  man 
stands  in  very  close  relation  to  his  mother's  local  group  and,  in 
many  tribes,  in  a  very  close  relation  to  its  sacra:  its  totems,  totem 
centres  and  totemic  rites. 

While  Australian  totemism  separates  the  local  groups  and 
gives  each  an  individuality  of  its  own,  it  also  links  the  groups  to- 
gether. For  while  each  group  is  specially  connected  with  certain 
parts  of  the  natural  order  (e.g.  with  rain,  or  with  kangaroo)  and 
with  certain  of  the  Beings  of  the  World- Dawn,  the  society  as 
a  whole  is  related  through  the  totemic  religion  to  the  whole 
order  of  nature  and  to  the  World- Dawn  as  a  whole.  This  is  best 
seen  in  another  kind  of  totemic  cult,  part  of  which  consists  of 
sacred  dramas  in  which  the  performers  impersonate  various  Dawn 
Beings.  Such  dramatic  dances  are  only  performed  at  those  religious 
meetings  at  which  a  number  of  local  groups  come  together,  and 
it  is  on  these  occasions  that  young  men  are  initiated  into  manhood 
and  into  the  religious  life  of  the  society. 


RELIGION  AND   SOCIETY  1 69 

Australian  society  is  not  merely  a  collection  of  separate 
local  groups;  it  is  also  a  body  of  persons  linked  together  in  the 
kinship  system.  Australian  totemism  is  a  cosmological  system  by 
which  the  phenomena  of  nature  are  incorporated  in  the  kinship 
organisation.  When  I  v/as  beginning  my  work  in  Australia  in  191  o, 
a  native  said  to  me,  'Bungurdi  (kangaroo)  [is]  my  kadja  (elder 
brother).'  This  simple  sentence  of  three  words  gives  the  clue 
to  an  understanding  of  Australian  totemism.  The  speaker  did  not 
mean  that  individuals  of  the  kangaroo  species  are  his  brothers. 
He  meant  that  to  the  kangaroo  species,  conceived  as  an  entity,  he 
stood  in  a  social  relation  analogous  to  that  in  which  a  man  stands  to 
his  elder  brother  in  the  kinship  system.  I  am  sorry  that  there  is  not 
time  on  this  occasion  to  expound  this  thesis  more  fully. 

The  account  I  have  just  given  of  Australian  totemism  differs 
considerably  from  that  given  by  Durkheim.  But  far  from  con- 
tradicting, it  confirms  Durkheim's  fundamental  general  theory 
as  to  the  social  function  of  the  totemic  religion  of  Australia  and 
its  rites.  The  two  kinds  of  totemic  cult  are  the  demonstration,  in 
symbolic  action,  of  the  structure  of  Australian  society  and  its 
foundations  in  a  mythical  and  sacred  past.  In  maintaining  the 
social  cohesion  and  equilibrium,  the  religion  plays  a  most  im- 
portant part.  The  rehgion  is  an  intrinsic  part  of  the  constitution 
of  society. 

I  have  dwelt,  if  only  cursorily,  with  two  types  of  religion: 
ancestor- worship  and  Australian  totemism.  In  both  of  them  it  is 
possible  to  demonstrate  the  close  correspondence  of  the  form  of 
religion  and  the  form  of  the  social  structure.  In  both  it  is  possible 
to  see  how  the  religious  rites  reaffirm  and  strengthen  the  senti- 
ments on  which  the  social  order  depends.  Here  then  are  results 
of  some  significance  for  our  problem.  They  point  to  a  certain  line 
of  investigation.  We  can  and  should  examine  other  religions  in  the 
light  of  the  results  already  reached.  But  to  do  this  we  must  study 
religions  in  action;  we  must  try  to  discover  the  effects  of  active 
participation  in  a  particular  cult,  first  the  direct  effects  on  the 
individual  and  then  the  further  effects  on  the  society  of  which  these 
individuals  are  members.  When  we  have  a  sufficient  number  of 
such  studies,  it  will  be  possible  to  establish  a  general  theory  of  the 
nature  of  religions  and  their  role  in  social  development. 

In  elaborating  such  a  general  theory  it  will  be  necessary  to 
determine  by  means  of  comparative  studies  the  relations  between 


lyo  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

religion  and  morality.  There  is  only  time  to  refer  very  briefly 
here  to  the  question  of  religion  and  morality.  As  representing  a 
theory  that  seems  to  be  widely  held,  I  quote  the  following  passages 
from  Tylor: 

One  great  element  of  religion,  that  moral  element  which  among  the 
higher  nations  forms  its  most  vital  part,  is  indeed  little  represented  in  the 
religion  of  the  lower  races. ^ 

The  comparison  of  savage  and  civilised  religions  brings  into  view, 
by  the  side  of  a  deep-lying  resemblance  in  their  philosophy,  a  deep-lying 
contrast  in  their  practical  action  on  human  life.  So  far  as  savage  religion 
can  stand  as  representing  natural  religion,  the  popular  idea  that  the  moral 
government  of  the  universe  is  an  essential  tenet  of  natural  religion  simply 
falls  to  the  ground.  Savage  animism  is  almost  devoid  of  that  ethical 
element  which  to  the  educated  modern  mind  is  the  very  mainspring  of 
practical  religion.  Not,  as  I  have  said,  that  morality  is  absent  from  the 
life  of  the  lower  races.  Without  a  code  of  morals,  the  very  existence  of 
the  rudest  tribe  would  be  impossible;  and  indeed  the  moral  standards 
of  even  savage  races  are  to  no  small  extent  well-defined  and  praiseworthy. 
But  these  ethical  laws  stand  on  their  own  ground  of  tradition  and  public 
opinion,  comparatively  independent  of  the  animistic  beliefs  and  rites 
which  exist  beside  them.  The  lower  animism  is  not  immoral,  it  is 
unmoral.  .  .  .  The  general  problem  of  the  relation  of  morality  to  religion 
is  difficult,  intricate,  and  requiring  immense  array  of  evidence.^ 

I  agree  with  Tylor  that  the  problem  of  the  relation  of  morality 
to  religion  is  difficult  and  intricate.  But  I  wish  to  question  the 
validity  of  the  distinction  he  makes  between  the  religions  of 
savage  sand  those  of  civilised  peoples,  and  of  his  statement  that 
the  moral  element  'is  little  represented  in^the  religion  of  the  lower 
races'.  I  suspect  that  when  this  view  is  held  it  often  means  only 
that  in  the  'lower  races'  the  religion  is  not  associated  with  the 
kind  of  morality  which  exists  in  contemporary  Western  societies. 
But  societies  diifer  in  their  systems  of  morals  as  in  other  aspects 
of  the  social  system,  and  what  we  have  to  examine  in  any  given 
society  is  the  relation  of  the  religion  or  religions  of  that  society 
to  their  particular  system  of  moraUty. 

Dr.  R.  F.  Fortune,  in  his  book  on  Manus  religion,  has  chal- 
lenged the  dictum  of  Tylor. ^  The  religion  of  Manus  is  what  may 
be  called  a  kind  of  spiritualism,  but  it  is  not  ancestor- worship  in 

^  Tylor,  Primitive  Culture,  3rd  ed.,  1891,  Vol.  I,  p.  427. 

-  op  cit.,  Vol.  II,  p.  360. 

'  R.  F.  Fortune,  Manus  Religion,  Philadelphia,  1935,  pp.  s  and  356.  Dr. 
Fortune's  book  is  a  useful  contribution  to  the  study  of  the  social  function  of 
religion  and  deals  with  a  religion  of  a  very  unusual  type. 


RELIGION  AND   SOCIETY  I71 

the  sense  in  which  I  have  used  the  term  in  this  lecture.  The 
Manus  code  of  morals  rigidly  forbids  sexual  intercourse  except 
between  husband  and  wife,  condemns  dishonesty  and  insists  on 
the  conscientious  fulfilment  of  obligations,  including  economic 
obligations,  towards  one's  relatives  and  others.  Offences  against 
the  moral  code  bring  down  on  the  offender,  or  on  his  household, 
punishment  from  the  spirits,  and  the  remedy  is  to  be  found  in 
confession  and  reparation  for  wrong. 

Let  us  now  reconsider  the  case  of  ancestor-worship.  In  the 
societies  which  practise  it,  the  most  important  part  of  the  moral 
code  is  that  which  concerns  the  conduct  of  the  individual  in 
relation  to  his  lineage  and  clan  and  the  individual  members  thereof. 
In  the  more  usual  form  of  ancestor- worship,  infractions  of  this 
code  fall  under  religious  or  supernatural  sanctions,  for  they 
are  offences  against  the  ancestors,  who  are  believed  to  send 
punishment. 

Again  we  may  take  as  an  example  of  the  lower  races  the 
aborigines  of  Australia.  Since  the  fundamental  social  structure  is 
a  complex  system  of  widely  extended  recognition  of  relations  of 
kinship,  the  most  important  part  of  the  moral  code  consists  of 
the  rules  of  behaviour  towards  kin  of  different  categories.  One  of 
the  most  immoral  actions  of  which  a  man  can  be  guilty  is  having 
sexual  relations  with  any  woman  who  does  not  belong  to  that 
category  of  his  kinsfolk  into  w^hich  he  may  legally  marry. 

The  moral  law  of  the  tribe  is  taught  to  young  men  in  the  very 
sacred  ceremonies  known  as  initiation  ceremonies.  I  will  deal  only 
with  the  Bora  ceremonies,  as  they  are  called,  of  some  of  the  tribes 
of  New  South  Wales.  These  ceremonies  were  instituted  in  the 
time  of  the  World-Da\Mi  by  Baiame,  who  killed  his  own  son 
Daramulun  (sometimes  identified  with  the  sacred  bull-roarer)  and 
on  the  third  day  brought  him  back  to  life.  As  the  ceremony  is 
conducted,  the  initiates  all  'die'  and  are  brought  back  to  life  on 
the  third  day.^ 

On  the  sacred  ceremonial  ground  where  these  initiations  take 
place  there  is  usually  an  image  of  Baiame  made  of  earth,  and 
sometimes  one  of  Baiame's  wife.  Beside  these  images  sacred  rites 

^  The  suggestion  has  been  made  that  we  have  here  the  influence  of  Christian- 
ity, but  that  opinion  can  be  dismissed.  The  idea  of  ritual  death  and  rebirth  is 
very  widespread  in  religion,  and  the  three-day  period  is  exemplified  every 
month  in  every  part  of  the  world  by  the  death  and  resurrection  of  the  moon. 


172  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

are  shown  to  the  initiates,  and  sacred  myths  about  Baiame  are 
recounted. 

Now  Baiame  instituted  not  only  the  initiation  ceremonies, 
which  are,  amongst  other  things,  schools  of  morals  for  young  men, 
but  also  the  kinship  system  with  its  rules  about  marriage  and 
behaviour  towards  different  categories  of  kin.  To  the  question, 
'Why  do  you  observe  these  complex  rules  about  marriage?' 
the  usual  answer  is,  'Because  Baiame  established  them'.  Thus 
Baiame  is  the  divine  law-giver,  or,  by  an  alternative  mode  of 
expression,  he  is  the  personification  of  the  tribal  laws  of 
morality. 

I  agree  with  Andrew  Lang  and  Father  Schmidt  that  Baiame 
thus  closely  resembles  one  aspect  of  the  God  of  the  Hebrews. 
But  Baiame  gives  no  assistance  in  war  as  Jehovah  did  for  the 
children  of  Israel,  nor  is  Baiame  the  ruler  or  controller  of  nature, 
of  storms  and  seasons.  That  position  is  held  by  another  deity,  the 
Rainbow- Serpent,  whose  image  in  earth  also  appears  on  the 
sacred  ceremonial  ground.  The  position  held  by  Baiame  is  that 
of  the  Divine  Being  who  established  the  most  important  rules  of 
morality  and  the  sacred  ceremonies  of  initiation. 

These  few  examples  will  perhaps  suffice  to  show  that  the  idea 
that  it  is  only  the  higher  religions  that  are  specially  concerned 
with  morahty,  and  that  the  moral  element  is  little  represented 
in  the  religions  of  the  lower  races,  is  decidedly  open  to  question. 
If  there  were  time  I  could  provide  instances  from  other  parts  of  the 
world. 

What  makes  these  problems  complex  is  the  fact  that  law, 
morality  and  religion  are  three  ways  of  controlling  human  conduct 
which  in  different  types  of  society  supplement  one  another,  and 
are  combined,  in  different  ways.  For  the  law  there  are  legal 
sanctions,  for  morality  there  are  the  sanctions  of  public  opinion 
and  of  conscience,  for  religion  there  are  religious  sanctions. 
A  single  wrongful  deed  may  fall  under  two  or  three  sanctions. 
Blasphemy  and  sacrilege  are  sins  and  so  subject  to  religious 
sanctions;  but  they  may  also  sometimes  be  punished  by  law  as 
crimes.  In  our  own  society  murder  is  immoral;  it  is  also  a 
crime  punishable  by  death  ;  and  it  is  also  a  sin  against  God,  so 
that  the  murderer,  after  his  sudden  exit  from  this  life  at  the 
hands  of  the  executioner,  must  face  an  eternity  of  torment  in 
the  fires  of  Hell. 


RELIGION  AND   SOCIETY  1 73 

Legal  sanctions  may  be  brought  into  action  in  instances 
where  there  is  no  question  of  morahty  or  immoraHty,  and  the 
same  is  true  of  rehgious  sanctions.  It  is  held  by  some  of  the  Fathers 
or  doctors  of  the  Christian  churches  that  an  upright  and  virtuous 
life  devoted  to  good  works  will  not  save  a  man  from  Hell  unless 
he  has  attained  grace  by  accepting  as  true  the  specific  doctrines 
taught  by  a  church, 

Xi^f'-reare  different  kinds  of  religious  sanctions.  The  penalty 
for  sin  may  be  conceived  simply  as  alienation  from  God.  Or 
there  may  be  a  belief  in  rewards  and  punishments  in  an  after-life. 
But  the  most  widespread  form  of  the  religious  sanction  is  the 
belief  that  certain  actions  produce  in  an  individual  or  in  a  com- 
munity a  condition  of  ritual  pollution,  or  uncleanness,  from  which 
it  is  necessary  to  be  purified.  Pollution  may  result  from  things 
done  unintentionally  and  unwittingly,  as  you  may  see  from  the 
fifth  chapter  of  the  Book  of  Leviticus.  One  who  unwittingly  has 
touched  any  unclean  thing,  such  as  the  carcase  of  an  unclean  beast, 
is  guilty  and  has  sinned  and  must  bear  his  iniquity.  He  must  make 
a  sacrifice,  a  trespass  offering,  by  which  he  may  be  cleansed  from 
his  sin. 

Ritual  uncleanness  does  not  in  itself  involve  moral  con- 
demnation. We  read  in  the  twelfth  chapter  of  the  same  Book  of 
Leviticus  that  the  Lord  instructed  Moses  that  a  woman  who  has 
borne  a  male  child  shall  be  unclean  for  seven  days  and  her 
purification  must  continue  for  a  further  three  and  thirty  days, 
during  which  she  shall  touch  no  hallowed  thing,  nor  come  into  the 
sanctuary.  If  the  child  she  bears  is  female,  the  first  period  of 
uncleanness  is  to  be  two  weeks  and  the  period  of  purification 
threescore-and-six  days.  Thus,  it  is  polluting,  but  no  one  can 
suppose  that  it  is  immoral,  to  bear  a  child,  and  more  polluting 
if  the  child  is  female  than  if  it  is  male. 

The  opposite  of  pollution  or  sinfulness  is  holiness.  But 
holiness  comes  not  from  leading  an  honest  and  upright  life,  but 
from  religious  exercises,  prayer  and  fasting,  the  performance  of 
penance,  meditation  and  the  reading  of  sacred  books.  In  Hinduism 
the  son  of  a  Brahmin  is  bom  holy;  the  son  of  a  leather-worker  is 
born  unclean. 

The  field  covered  by  morality  and  that  covered  by  religion 
are  dift'erent;  but  either  in  primitive  or  in  civilised  societies  there 
may  be  a  region  in  which  they  overlap. 


M 
u 


174  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION    IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

To  return  to  our  main  topic,  a  writer  who  has  dealt  with 
the  social  function  of  religions  on  the  basis  of  a  comparative 
study  is  Loisy,  who  devotes  to  the  subject  a  few  pages  of  the  con- 
cluding chapter  of  his  valuable  Essai  historique  sur  le  Sacrificed 
Although  he  differs  from  Durkheim  in  some  matters,  his  funda- 
mental theory  is,  if  not  identical,  at  any  rate  very  similar  to  that 
of  the  earlier  writer.  Speaking  of  what  he  calls  the  sacred  action 
{V action  sacree),  of  which  the  most  characteristic  form  is  the  rite  of 
sacrifice,  he  writes: 

We  have  seen  its  rl6e  in  human  societies,  of  which  it  has  maintained 
and  strengthened  the  social  bonds,  if  indeed  it  has  not  contributed  in  a 
large  measure  to  creating  them.  It  was,  in  certain  respects,  the  expression 
of  them;  but  man  is  so  made  that  he  becomes  more  firmly  fixed  in  his 
sentiments  by  expressing  them.  The  sacred  action  was  the  expression 
of  social  life,  of  social  aspirations,  it  has  necessarily  been  a  factor  of 
society.  .  .  . 

Before  we  condemn  out  of  hand  the  mirage  of  religion  and  the  ap- 
paratus of  sacrifice  as  a  simple  waste  of  social  resources  and  forces,  it  is 
proper  to  observe  that,  religion  having  been  the  form  of  social  conscience, 
and  sacrifice  the  expression  of  this  conscience,  the  loss  was  compensated 
by  a  gain,  and  that,  so  far  as  purely  material  losses  are  concerned,  there 
is  really  no  occasion  to  dwell  on  them.  Moreover  the  kind  of  sacred 
contribution  that  was  required,  without  real  utility  as  to  the  effect  that 
was  expected  from  it,  was  an  intrinsic  part  of  the  system  of  renuncia- 
tions, of  contributions  which,  in  every  human  society,  are  the  condition 
of  its  equilibrium  and  its  conservation.  ^ 

But  besides  this  definition  of  the  social  function  in  terms 
of  social  cohesion  and  continuity,  Loisy  seeks  for  what  he  calls  a 
general  formula  {formule  generale)  in  which  to  sum  up  the  part 
that  religion  has  played  in  human  life.  Such  a  formula  is  useful  so 
long  as  we  remember  that  it  is  only  a  formula.  The  one  that 
Loisy  offers  is  that  magic  and  religion  have  served  to  give  men 
confidence. 

In  the  most  primitive  societies  it  is  magic  that  gives  man 
confidence  in  face  of  the  difficulties  and  uncertainties,  the  real  and 
imaginary  dangers  with  which  he  is  surrounded. 


A  la  merci  des  elements,  des  saisons,  de  ce  que  la  terre  lui  donne  ou 
lui  refuse,  des  bonnes  ou  des  mauvaises  chances  de  sa  chasse  ou  de  sa 
peche,  aussi  du  hasard  de  ses  combats  avec  ses  semblables,  il  croit  trouver 
le  moyen  de  regulariser  par  des  simulacres  d'action  ces  chances  plus  ou 

^  1920,  pp.  531-40.  ^  op  cit.,  pp.  535-7. 


RELIGION  AND  SOCIETY  1 75 

moins  incertaines.  Ce  qu'il  fait  ne  sert  a  rien  par  rapport  au  but  qu'il  se 
propose,  mais  il  prend  confiance  en  ses  entreprises  et  en  lui-meme, 
il  ose,  et  c'est  en  osant  que  reellement  il  obtient  plus  ou  moins  ce  qu'il 
veut.  Confiance  rudimentaire,  et  pour  une  humble  vie;  mais  c'est  le 
commencement  du  courage  moral.^ 

This  is  the  same  theory  that  was  later  developed  by  IVIalinowski 
in  reference  to  the  magical  practices  of  the  Trobriand  Islanders. 

At  a  somewhat  higher  stage  of  development,  'when  the  social 
organism  has  been  perfected,  when  the  tribe  has  become  a  people, 
and  this  people  has  its  gods,  its  religion,  it  is  by  this  religion  itself 
that  the  strength  of  the  national  conscience  is  measured,  and  it 
is  in  the  service  of  national  gods  that  men  find  a  pledge  of  security 
in  the  present,  of  prosperity  in  the  future.  The  gods  are  as  it  were 
the  expression  of  the  confidence  that  the  people  has  in  itself; 
but  it  is  in  the  cult  of  the  gods  that  this  confidence  is  nourished.'^ 

At  a  still  higher  stage  of  social  development,  the  religions 
which  give  men  a  promise  of  immortality  give  him  thereby  an 
assurance  which  permits  him  to  bear  courageously  the  burdens 
of  his  present  life  and  face  the  most  onerous  obligations.  'It  is  a 
higher  and  more  moral  form  of  confidence  in  life. '^     ; 

To  me  this  formula  seems  unsatisfactory  in  tliat  it  lays  stress 
on  what  is  only  one  side  of  the  religious  (or  magical)  attitude.  I 
offer  as  an  alternative  the  formula  that  religion  develops  in  man- 
kind what  may  be  called  a  §gnse  of  dependence.  What  I  mean  by 
this  can  best  be  explained  by  an  example.  In  an  ancestor-wor- 
shipping tribe  of  South  Africa,  a  man  feels  that  he  is  dependent 
on  his  ancestors.  From  them  he  has  received  his  life  and  the  cattle 
that  are  his  inheritance.  To  them  he  looks  to  send  him  children 
and  to  multiply  his  cattle  and  in  other  ways  to  care  for  his  well- 
being.  This  is  one  side  of  the  matter;  on  his  ancestors  he  can 
depend.  The  other  side  is  the  belief  that  the  ancestors  watch  over 
his  conduct,  and  that  if  he  fails  in  his  duties  they  will  not  only 
cease  to  send  him  blessings,  but  will  visit  him  with  sickness  or  . 
some  other  misfortune.  He  cannot  stand  alone  and  depend  only  J 
on  his  own  efforts;  on  his  ancestors  he  must  depend. 

We  may  say  that  the  beUefs  of  the  African  ancestor- worshipper 
are  illusory  and  his  offerings  to  his  gods  really  useless;  that  the 
dead  of  his  lineage  do  not  really  send  him  either  blessings  or 

'  op  cit.,  p.  533.  *  loc  cit.  *  op  cit.,  p.  534. 


1 76  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

punishments.  But  the  Confucians  have  shown  us  that  a  rehgion 
hke  ancestor-worship  can  be  rationaUsed  and  freed  from  those 
illusory  beliefs  that  we  call  superstition.  For  in  the  rites  of  com- 
memoration of  the  ancestors  it  is  sufficient  that  the  participants 
should  express  their  reverential  gratitude  to  those  from  whom  they 
have  received  their  life,  and  their  sense  of  duty  towards  those  not 
yet  born,  to  whom  they  in  due  course  will  stand  in  the  position 
of  revered  ancestors.  There  still  remains  the  sense  of  dependence. 
The  living  depend  on  those  of  the  past;  they  have  duties  to  those 
living  in  the  present  and  to  those  of  the  future  who  will  depend 
on  them. 

I  suggest  to  you  that  what  makes  and  keeps  a  man  a  social 
animal  is  not  some  herd  instinct,  but  the  sense  of  dependence  in 
the  innumerable  forms  that  it  takes.  The  process  of  socialisation 
begins  on  the  first  day  of  an  infant's  life  and  it  has  to  learn  that  it 
both  can  and  must  depend  on  its  parents.  From  them  it  has  comfort 
and  succour;  but  it  must  submit  also  to  their  control.  What  I 
am  calling  the  sense  of  dependence  always  has  these  two  sides. 
We  can  face  life  and  its  chances  and  difficulties  with  confidence 
when  we  know  that  there  are  powers,  forces  and  events  on 
which  we  can  rely,  but  we  must  submit  to  the  control  of  our 
conduct  by  rules  which  are  imposed.  The  entirely  asocial  in- 
dividual would  be  one  who  thought  that  he  could  be  completely 
independent,  relying  only  on  himself,  asking  for  no  help  and 
recognising  no  duties. 

I  have  tried  to  present  to  you  .a  theory  of  the  social  function  of 
religion.  This  theory  has  been  developed  by  the  work  of  such  men 
as  Robertson  Smith,  Fustel  de  Coulanges,  Durkheim,  Loisy. 
It  is  the  theory  that  has  guided  my  own  studies  for  nearly  forty 
years.  I  have  thought  it  worth  while  to  indicate  that  it  existed 
in  embryo  in  the  writings  of  Chinese  philosophers  more  than 
twenty  centuries  ago. 

Like  any  other  scientific  theory  it  is  provisional,  subject  to 
revision  and  modification  in  the  light  of  future  research.  It  is 
offered  as  providing  what  seems  likely  to  be  a  profitable  method 
of  investigation.  What  is  needed  to  test  and  further  elaborate  the 
theory  is  a  number  of  systematic  studies  of  various  types  of  religion 
in  relation  to  social  systems  in  which  they  occur. 

I  will  summarise  the  suggestions  I  have  made: 


RELIGION  AND   SOCIETY  lyy 

1.  To  understand  a  particular  religion  we  must  study  its 
effects.  The  religion  must  therefore  _be_studied  in  action. 

2.  Since  human  conduct  is  in  large  part  controlled  or  directed 
by  what  have  been  called  sentiments,  conceived  as  mental 
dispositions,  it  is  necessary  to  discover  as  far  as  possible 
what  are  the  senlkoents  that  are  developed  in  the  individual 
as  the  result  of  his  participation  in  a  particular  rehgious 
cuh. 

3.  In  the  study  of  any  religion  we  must  first^pf  all  examine 
the  specifically  religious  actions,  the  ceremonies  and  the 
collective  or  individual  rites. 

4.  The  emphasis  on  belief  in  specific  doctrines  which  charac- 
terises some  modem  religions  seems  to  be  the  result  of 
certain  social  developments  in  societies  of  complex  structure. 

5.  In  some  societies  there  is  a  direct  and  immediate  relation 
between  the  religion  and  the  social  structure.  This  has  been 
illustrated  by  ancestor-worship  and  Australian  totemism. 
It  is  also  true  of  what  w^e  may  call  national  religions,  such 
as  that  of  the  Hebrews  or  those  of  the  city  states  of  Greece 
and  Rome.^  But  where  there  comes  into  existence  a  separate 
independent  religious  structure  by  the  formation  of  different 
churches  or  sects  or  cult-groups  within  a  people,  the 
relation  of  religion  to  the  total  social  structure  is  in  many 
respects  indirect  and  not  always  easy  to  trace. 

6.  As  a  general  formula  (for  whatever  such  a  formula  may  be 
worth)  it  is  suggested  that  what  is  expressed  in  all  rehgions 
is  what  I  have  called  the  sense  of  dependence  in  its  double 
aspect,  and  that  it  is  by  constantly  maintaining  this  sense 
of  dependence  that  religions  perform  their  social  function. 

^  *  .  .  .  among  the  ancients  what  formed  the  bond  of  every  society  was  a 
worship.  Just  as  a  domestic  altar  held  the  members  of  a  family  grouped  about 
it,  so  the  city  was  the  collective  group  of  those  who  had  the  same  protecting 
deities,  and  who  performed  the  religious  ceremony  at  the  same  altar.'  Fustel 
de  Coulanges,  op  cit.,  p.  193. 


CHAPTER     IX 

ON  THE   CONCEPT   OF   FUNCTION   IN 
SOCIAL   SCIENCE! 

THE  concept  of  function  applied  to  human  societies  is 
based  on  an  analogy  between  social  life  and  organic  life. 
The  recognition  of  the  analogy  and  of  some  of  its  implica- 
tions is  not  new.  In  the  nineteenth  century  the  analogy,  the  concept 
of  function,  and  the  word  itself  appear  frequently  in  social  philo- 
sophy and  sociology.  So  far  as  I  know  the  first  systematic 
formulation  of  the  concept  as  applying  to  the  strictly  scientific 
study  of  society  was  that  of  Emile  Durkheim  in  1895.  [Rigles  de  la 
Methode  Sociologique.) 

Durkheim's  definition  is  that  the  'function'  of  a  social  in- 
stitution is  the  correspondence  between  it  and  the  needs  (besoins 
in  French)  of  the  social  organism.  This  definition  requires  some 
elaboration.  In  the  first  place,  to  avoid  possible  ambiguity  and 
in  particular  the  possibility  of  a  teleological  interpretation,  I 
would  like  to  substitute  for  the  term  'needs'  the  term  'necessary 
conditions  of  existence',  or,  if  the  term  'need'  is  used,  it  is  to  be 
understood  only  in  this  sense.  It  may  be  here  noted,  as  a  point 
to  be  returned  to,  that  any  attempt  to  apply  this  concept  of  function 
in  social  science  involves  the  assumption  that  there  are  necessary 
conditions  of  existence  for  human  societies  just  as  there  are  for 
animal  organisms,  and  that  they  can  be  discovered  by  the  proper 
kind  of  scientific  enquiry. 

For  the  further  elucidation  of  the  concept  it  is  convenient  to 
use  the  analogy  between  social  life  and  organic  life.  Like  all 
analogies  it  has  to  be  used  with  care.  An  animal  organism  is  an 
agglomeration  of  cells  and  interstitial  fluids  arranged  in  relation 
to  one  another  not  as  an  aggregate  but  as  an  integrated  living 
whole.  For  the  biochemist,  it  is  a  complexly  integrated  system 
of  complex  molecules.  The  system  of  relations  by  which  these 

^  This  paper,  which  is  based  on  comments  that  I  made  on  a  paper  read  by 
Dr.  Lesser  to  the  American  Anthropological  Association,  is  reprinted  from 
the  American  Anthropologist,  Vol.  XXXVII,  p.  3,  1935,  where  it  accompanied 
Dr.  Lesser's  paper. 

178 


ON   THE   CONCEPT   OF   FUNCTION    IN   SOCIAL   SCIENCE  1 79 

units  are  related  is  the  organic  structure.  As  the  terms  are  here 
used  the  organism  is  not  itself  the  structure;  it  is  a  collection  of 
units  (cells  or  molecules)  arranged  in  a  structure,  i.e.  in  a  set  of 
relations;  the  organism  has  a  structure.  Two  mature  animals  of  the 
same  species  and  sex  consist  of  similar  units  combined  in  a  similar 
structure.  The  structure  is  thus  to  be  defined  as  a  set  of  relations 
between  entities.  (The  structure  of  a  cell  is  in  the  same  way  aj 
set  of  relations  between  complex  molecules,  and  the  structure  of 
an  atom  is  a  set  of  relations  between  electrons  and  protons.)  As 
long  as  it  lives  the  organism  preserves  a  certain  continuity  of 
structure  although  it  does  not  preserve  the  complete  identity  of 
its  constituent  parts.  It  loses  some  of  its  constituent  molecules 
by  respiration  or  excretion;  it  takes  in  others  by  respiration  and 
alimentary  absorption.  Over  a  period  its  constituent  cells  do  not 
remain  the  same.  But  the  structural  arrangement  of  the  constituent 
units  does  remain  similar.  The  process  by  which  this  structural 
continuity  of  the  organism  is  maintained  is  called  life.  The 
life-process  consists  of  the  activities  and  interactions  of  the 
constituent  units  of  the  organism,  the  cells,  and  the  organs  into 
which  the  cells  are  united. 

As  the  word  function  is  here  being  used  the  life  of  an  organism 
is  conceived  as  the  functioning  of  its  structure.  It  is  through  and 
by  the  continuity  of  the  functioning  that  the  continuity  of  the 
structure  is  preserved.  If  we  consider  any  recurrent  part  of  the 
life-process,  such  as  respiration,  digestion,  etc.,  its  function 
is  the  part  it  plays  in,  the  contribution  it  makes  to,  the  life  of 
the  organism  as  a  whole.  As  the  terms  are  here  being  used  a  cell 
or  an  organ  has  an  activity  and  that  activity  has  a  function.  It  is 
true  that  we  commonly  speak  of  the  secretion  of  gastric  fluid  as  a 
'function'  of  the  stomach.  As  the  words  are  here  used  we  should 
say  that  this  is  an  'activity'  of  the  stomach,  the  'function'  of  which 
is  to  change  the  proteins  of  food  into  a  form  in  which  these  are 
absorbed  and  distributed  by  the  blood  to  the  tissues.^  We  may  note 
that  the  function  of  a  recurrent  physiological  process  is  thus  a 
correspondence  between  it  and  the  needs  (i.e.  necessary  conditions 
of  existence)  of  the  organism. 

^  The  insistence  on  this  precise  form  of  terminology  is  only  for  the  sake 
of  the  analogy  that  is  to  be  drawn.  I  have  no  objection  to  the  use  of  the  term 
function  in  physiology  to  denote  both  the  activity  of  an  organ  and  the  results 
of  that  activity  in  maintaining  life. 


l8o  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN    PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

If  we  set  out  upon  a  systematic  investigation  of  the  nature  of 
organisms  and  organic  life  there  are  three  sets  of  problems 
presented  to  us.  (There  are,  in  addition,  certain  other  sets  of 
problems  concerning  aspects  or  characteristics  of  organic  life  with 
\  which  we  are  not  here  concerned.)  One  is  that  of  morphology — 
what  kinds  of  organic  structures  are  there,  what  similarities  and 
variations  do  they  show,  and  how  can  they  be  classified?  Second 
are  the  problems  of  physiology — how,  in  general,  do  organic 
structures  function,  what,  therefore,  is  the  nature  of  the  life- 
process?  Third  are  the  problems  of  evolution  or  development — 
how  do  new  types  of  organisms  come  into  existence? 

To  turn  from  organic  life  to  social  life,  if  we  examine  such  a 
community  as  an  African  or  Australian  tribe  we  can  recognise 
the  existence  of  a  social  structure.  Individual  human  beings,  the 
essential  units  in  this  instance,  are  connected  by  a  definite  set  of 
social  relations  into  an  integrated  whole.  The  continuity  of  the 
social  structure,  like  that  of  an  organic  structure,  is  not  destroyed 
by  changes  in  the  units.  Individuals  may  leave  the  society,  by 
death  or  otherwise;  others  may  enter  it.  The  continuity  of  structure 
is  maintained  by  the  process  of  social  life,  which  consists  of  the 
activities  and  interactions  of  the  individual  human  beings  and  of 
the  organised  groups  into  which  they  are  united.  The  social  life 
of  the  community  is  here  defined  as  the  functioning  of  the  social 
structure.  The  function  of  any  recurrent  activity,  such  as  the 
punishment  of  a  crime,  or  a  funeral  ceremony,  is  the  part  it  plays 
in  the  social  life  as  a  whole  and  therefore  the  contribution  it  makes 
to  the  maintenance  of  the  structural  continuity. 

The  concept  of  function  as  here  defined  thus  involves  the 
notion  of  a  structure  consisting  of  a  set  of  relations  amongst  unit 
entities,  the  continuity  of  the  structure  being  maintained  by  a  life- 
process  made  up  of  the  activities  of  the  constituent  units. 

If,  with  these  concepts  in  mind,  we  set  out  on  a  systematic 
investigation  of  the  nature  of  human  society  and  of  social  life, 
we  find  presented  to  us  three  sets  of  problems.  First,  the  problems 
of  social  morphology — ^what  kinds  of  social  structures  are  there, 
what  are  their  similarities  and  differences,  how  are  they  to  be 
classified?  Second,  the  problems  of  social  physiolog}'^ — how  do 
social  structures  function?  Third,  the  problems  of  development — 
how  do  new  types  of  social  structure  come  into  existence? 

Two  important  points  where  the  analogy  between  organism  and 


ON  THE   CONCEPT   OF   FUNCTION   IN   SOCIAL   SCIENCE  l8l 

society  breaks  down  must  be  noted.  In  an  animal  organism  it  is 
possible  to  observe  the  organic  structure  to  some  extent  in- 
dependently of  its  functioning.  It  is  therefore  possible  to  make  a 
morphology  which  is  independent  of  physiology.  But  in  human 
society  the  social  structure  as  a  w  hole  can  only  be  observed  in  its 
functioning.  Some  of  the  features  of  social  structure,  such  as 
the  geographical  distribution  of  individuals  and  groups  can  be 
directly  observed,  but  most  of  the  social  relations  which  in  their 
totality  constitute  the  structure,  such  as  relations  of  father  and 
son,  buyer  and  seller,  ruler  and  subject,  cannot  be  observed 
except  in  the  social  activities  in  which  the  relations  are  functioning. 
It  follows  that  a  social  morphology  cannot  be  established  in- 
dependently of  a  social  physiology. 

The  second  point  is  that  an  animal  organism  does  not,  in  the 
course  of  its  life,  change  its  structural  type.  A  pig  does  not  become 
a  hippopotamus.  (The  development  of  the  animal  from  ger- 
mination to  maturity  is  not  a  change  of  type  since  the  process  in 
all  its  stages  is  typical  for  the  species.)  On  the  other  hand  a 
society  in  the  course  of  its  history  can  and  does  change  its  structural 
type  without  any  breach  of  continuity. 

By  the  definition  here  offered  'function'  is  the  contribution 
which  a  partial  activity  makes  to  the  total  activity  of  which  it  is  a 
part.  The  function  of  a  particular  social  usage  is  the  contribution 
it  makes  to  the  total  social  life  as  the  functioning  of  the  total  social 
system.  Such  a  view  implies  that  a  social  system  (the  total  social 
structure  of  a  society  together  with  the  totality  of  social  usages 
in  which  that  structure  appears  and  on  which  it  depends  for  its 
continued  existence)  has  a  certain  kind  of  unity,  which  we  may 
speak  of  as  a  functional  unity.  We  may  define  it  as  a  condition 
in  which  all  parts  of  the  social  system  work  together  with  a 
sufficient  degree  of  harmony  or  internal  consistency,  i.e.  without 
producing  persistent  conflicts  which  can  neither  be  resolved  nor 
regulated.^ 

This  idea  of  the  functional  unity  of  a  social  system  is,  of  course,  [ 
a  hypothesis.  But  it  is  one  which,  to  the  functionalist,  it  seems  i 
worth  while  to  test  by  systematic  examination  of  the  facts. 

There  is  another  aspect  of  functional  theory  that  should  be 
briefly  mentioned.  To   return   to  the  analogy  of  social  life  and 

^  Opposition,  i.e.  organised  and  regulated  antagonism,  is,  of  course,  an 
essential  feature  of  every  social  system. 


1 82  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

organic  life,  we  recognise  that  an  organism  may  function  more  or 
less  efficiently  and  so  we  set  up  a  special  science  of  pathology 
to  deal  with  all  phenomena  of  disfunction.  We  distinguish  in  an 
organism  what  we  call  health  and  disease.  The  Greeks  of  the  fifth 
century  B.C.  thought  that  one  might  apply  the  same  notion  to 
society,  to  the  city-state,  distinguishing  conditions  of  eunomia, 
good  order,  social  health,  from  dysnomia,  disorder,  social  ill- 
health.  In  the  nineteenth  century  Durkheim,  in  his  application 
of  the  notion  of  function,  sought  to  lay  the  basis  for  a  scientific 
social  pathology,  based  on  a  morphology  and  a  physiology.^ 
In  his  works,  particularly  those  on  suicide  and  the  division  of 
labour,  he  attempted  to  find  objective  criteria  by  which  to  judge 
whether  a  given  society  at  a  given  time  is  normal  or  pathological, 
eunomic  or  dysnomic.  For  example,  he  tried  to  show  that  the 
increase  of  the  rate  of  suicide  in  many  countries  during  part  of  the 
nineteenth  century  is  symptomatic  of  a  dysnomic  or,  in  his 
terminology,  anomic,  social  condition.  Probably  there  is  no 
sociologist  who  would  hold  that  Durkheim  really  succeeded  in 
establishing  an  objective  basis  for  a  science  of  social  pathology.  ^ 

In  relation  to  organic  structures  we  can  find  strictly  objective 
criteria  by  which  to  distinguish  disease  from  health,  pathological 
from  normal,  for  disease  is  that  which  either  threatens  the  organ- 
ism with  death  (the  dissolution  of  its  structure)  or  interferes  with 
the  activities  which  are  characteristic  of  the  organic  type.  Societies 
do  not  die  in  the  same  sense  that  animals  die  and  therefore  we 
cannot  define  dysnomia  as  that  which  leads,  if  unchecked,  to  the 
death  of  a  society.  Further,  a  society  differs  from  an  organism 
in  that  it  can  change  its  structural  type,  or  can  be  absorbed  as 
an  integral  part  of  a  larger  society.  Therefore  we  cannot  define 
dysnomia  as  a  disturbance  of  the  usual  activities  of  a  social  type 
(as  Durkheim  tried  to  do). 

Let  us  return  for  a  moment  to  the  Greeks.  They  conceived 
the  health  of  an  organism  and  the  eunomia  of  a  society  as  being 
in  each  instance  a  condition  of  the  harmonious  working  together 

*  For  what  is  here  called  dysnomia  Durkheim  used  the  term  anomia  (anomie 
in  French).  This  is  to  my  mind  inappropriate.  Health  and  disease,  eunomia  and 
dysnomia,  are  essentially  relative  terms. 

^  I  would  personally  agree  in  the  main  with  the  criticisms  of  Roger  Lacombe 
(La  Methode  Sociologique  de  Durkheim,  1926,  ch.  iv)  on  Durldieim's  general 
theory  of  social  pathology,  and  with  the  criticisms  of  Durkheim 's  treatment 
of  suicide  presented  by  Halbwachs,  Les  Causes  du  Suicide. 


ON   THE   CONCEPT   OF   FUNCTION   IN   SOCIAL   SCIENCE         1 83 

of  its  parts.^  Now  this,  where  society  is  concerned,  is  the  same 
thing  as  what  was  considered  above  as  the  functional  unity  or 
inner  consistency  of  a  social  system,  and  it  is  suggested  that  for  the 
degree  of  functional  unity  of  a  particular  society  it  may  be  possible 
to  establish  a  purely  objective  criterion.  Admittedly  this  cannot  be 
done  at  present;  but  the  science  of  human  society  is  as  yet  in  its 
extreme  infancy.  So  that  it  may  be  that  we  should  say  that,  while 
an  organism  that  is  attacked  by  a  virulent  disease  will  react  thereto, 
and,  if  its  reaction  fails,  will  die,  a  society  that  is  thrown  into  a 
condition  of  functional  disunity  or  inconsistency  (for  this  we  now 
provisionally  identify  with  dysnomia)  will  not  die,  except  in  such 
comparatively  rare  instances  as  an  Australian  tribe  oversvhelmed 
by  the  white  man's  destructive  force,  but  will  continue  to  struggle 
toward  some  sort  of  eunomia,  some  kind  of  social  health,  and  may, 
in  the  course  of  this,  change  its  structural  type.  This  process,  it 
seems,  the  'functionalist'  has  ample  opportunities  of  observing 
at  the  present  day,  in  native  peoples  subjected  to  the  domination 
of  the  civilised  nations,  and  in  those  nations  themselves.  ^ 

Space  will  not  allow  a  discussion  here  of  another  aspect  of 
functional  theory,  viz.  the  question  whether  change  of  social  type 
is  or  is  not  dependent  on  function,  i.e.  on  the  laws  of  social  physio- 
logy. My  own  view  is  that  there  is  such  a  dependence  and  that  its 
nature  can  be  studied  in  the  development  of  the  legal  and  political 
institutions,  the  economic  systems  and  the  religions  of  Europe 
through  the  last  tw-enty-five  centuries.  For  the  preliterate  societies 
with  which  anthropology  is  concerned,  it  is  not  possible  to  study 
the  details  of  long  processes  of  change  of  type.  The  one  kind  of 
change  which  the  anthropologist  can  observe  is  the  disintegration 
of  social  structures.  Yet  even  here  we  can  observe  and  compare 
spontaneous  movements  towards  reintegration.  We  have,  for 
instance,  in  Africa,  in  Oceania,  and  in  America  the  appearance  of 
new  reUgions  which  can  be  interpreted  on  a  functional  hypothesis 

^  See,  for  example,  the  Fourth  Book  of  Plato's  Republic. 

^  To  avoid  misunderstanding  it  is  perhaps  necessary  to  observe  that  this 
distinction  of  eunomic  and  dysnomic  social  conditions  does  not  give  us  any 
evaluation  of  these  societies  as  'good'  or  'bad'.  A  savage  tribe  practising  polyg- 
amy, cannibalism,  and  sorcery  can  possibly  show  a  higher  degree  of  functional 
unity  or  consistency  than  the  United  States  of  1935.  This  objective  judgment, 
for  such  it  must  be  if  it  is  to  be  scientific,  is  something  very  different  from  any 
judgment  as  to  which  of  the  two  social  systems  is  the  better,  the  more  to  be 
desired  or  approved. 


184  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

as  attempts  to  relieve  a  condition  of  social  dysnomia  produced 
by  the  rapid  modification  of  the  social  Hfe  through  contact  with 
white  civilisation. 

The  concept  of  function  as  defined  above  constitutes  a 
'working  hypothesis'  by  which  a  number  of  problems  are  form- 
ulated for  investigation.  No  scientific  enquiry  is  possible  without 
some  such  formulation  of  working  hypotheses.  Two  remarks  are 
necessary  here.  One  is  that  the  hypothesis  does  not  require  the 
dogmatic  assertion  that  everything  in  the  life  of  every  community 
has  a  function.  It  only  requires  the  assumption  that  it  may 
have  one,  and  that  we  are  justified  in  seeking  to  discover  it.  The 
second  is  that  what  appears  to  be  the  same  social  usage  in  two 
societies  may  have  different  functions  in  the  two.  Thus  the  practice 
of  celibacy  in  the  Roman  Catholic  Church  of  today  has  very 
different  functions  from  those  of  ceUbacy  in  the  early  Christian 
Church.  In  other  words,  in  order  to  define  a  social  usage,  and 
therefore  in  order  to  make  valid  comparisons  between  the  usages 
of  different  peoples  or  periods,  it  is  necessary  to  consider  not 
merely  the  form  of  the  usage  but  also  its  function.  On  this  basis, 
for  example,  belief  in  a  Supreme  Being  in  a  simple  society  is 
something  different  from  such  a  belief  in  a  modern  civilised 
community. 

The  acceptance  of  the  functional  hypothesis  or  point  of  view 
outlined  above  results  in  the  recognition  of  a  vast  number  of 
problems  for  the  solution  of  which  there  are  required  wide  com- 
parative studies  of  societies  of  many  diverse  types  and  also  in- 
tensive studies  of  as  many  single  societies  as  possible.  In  field 
studies  of  the  simpler  peoples  it  leads,  first  of  all,  to  a  direct  study 
of  the  social  life  of  the  community  as  the  functioning  of  a  social 
structure,  and  of  this  there  are  several  examples  in  recent  literature. 
Since  the  function  of  a  social  activity  is  to  be  found  by  examining 
its  effects  upon  individuals,  these  are  studied,  either  in  the  average 
individual  or  in  both  average  and  exceptional  individuals.  Further, 
the  hypothesis  leads  to  attempts  to  investigate  directly  the  func- 
tional consistency  or  unity  of  a  social  system  and  to  determine  as 
far  as  possible  in  each  instance  the  nature  of  that  unity.  Such  field 
studies  will  obviously  be  different  in  many  ways  from  studies 
carried  out  from  other  points  of  view,  e.g.  the  ethnological  point 
of  view  that  lays  emphasis  on  diffusion.  We  do  not  have  to  say 
that  one  point  of  view  is  better  than  another,  but  only  that  they 


ON   THE   CONCEPT   OF   FUNCTION   IN   SOCIAL   SCIENCE         1 85 

are  different,  and  any  particular  piece  of  work  should  be  judged 
in  reference  to  what  it  aims  to  do. 

If  the  view  here  outlined  is  taken  as  one  form  of  'functionalism', 
a  few  remarks  on  Dr.  Lesser's  paper  become  permissible.  He 
makes  reference  to  a  difference  of  'content'  in  functional  and  non- 
functional anthropology.  From  the  point  of  view  here  presented 
the  'content'  or  subject-matter  of  social  anthropology  is  the  whole 
social  life  of  a  people  in  all  its  aspects.  For  convenience  of  handling 
it  is  often  necessary  to  devote  special  attention  to  some  particular 
part  or  aspect  of  the  social  life,  but  if  functionalism  means 
anything  at  all  it  does  mean  the  attempt  to  see  the  social  life  of  a  \  - 
people  as  a  whole,  as  a  functional  unity.  ' 

Dr.  Lesser  speaks  of  the  functionalist  as  stressing  'the 
psychological  aspects  of  culture',  I  presume  that  he  here  refers 
to  the  functionalist's  recognition  that  the  usages  of  a  society  work 
or  'function'  only  through  their  effects  in  the  life,  i.e.  in  the 
thoughts,  sentiments  and  actions  of  individuals. 

The  'functionalist'  point  of  view  here  presented  does  therefore 
imply  that  we  have  to  investigate  as  thoroughly  as  possible  all 
aspects  of  social  life,  considering  them  in  relation  to  one  another, 
and  that  an  essential  part  of  the  task  is  the  investigation  of  the  1 
individual  and  of  the  way  in  which  he  is  moulded  by  or  adjusted  ^ 
to  the  social  life. 

Turning  from  content  to  method  Dr.  Lesser  seems  to  find 
some  conflict  between  the  functional  point  of  view  and  the  his- 
torical. This  is  reminiscent  of  the  attempts  formerly  made  to  see 
a  conflict  between  sociology  and  history.  There  need  be  no  con- 
flict, but  there  is  a  difference. 

There  is  not,  and  cannot  be,  any  conflict  between  the  functional 
hypothesis  and  the  view  that  any  culture,  any  social  system,  is  the 
end-result  of  a  unique  series  of  historical  accidents.  The  process  of 
development  of  the  race-horse  from  its  five-toed  ancestor  was  a 
unique  series  of  historical  accidents.  This  does  not  conflict  with 
the  view  of  the  physiologist  that  the  horse  of  today  and  all  the 
antecedent  forms  conform  or  conformed  to  physiological  laws,  i.e. 
to  the  necessary  conditions  of  organic  existence.  Palaeontology  and 
physiology  are  not  in  conflict.  One  'explanation'  of  the  race-horse 
is  to  be  found  in  its  history — how  it  came  to  be  just  what  it  is  and 
where  it  is.  Another  and  entirely  independent  'explanation'  is  to 
show  how  the  horse  is  a  special  exemplification  of  physiological 


1 86  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

laws.  Similarly  one  'explanation'  of  a  social  system  will  be  its 
history,  where  we  know  it — the  detailed  account  of  how  it  came 
to  be  what  it  is  and  where  it  is.  Another  'explanation'  of  the  same 
system  is  obtained  by  showing  (as  the  functionalist  attempts  to  do) 
that  it  is  a  special  exemplification  of  laws  of  social  physiology 
■or  social  functioning.  The  two  kinds  of  explanation  do  not 
conflict,  but  supplement  one  another.^ 

The  functional  hypothesis  is  in  conflict  with  two  views  that 
are  held  by  some  ethnologists,  and  it  is  probably  these,  held  as 
they  often  are  without  precise  formulation,  that  are  the  cause  of 
the  antagonism  to  that  approach.  One  is  the  '  shreds  and  patches' 
theory  of  culture,  the  designation  being  taken  from  a  phrase  of 
Professor  Lowie^  when  he  speaks  of  'that  planless  hodge-podge, 
that  thing  of  shreds  and  patches  called  civilisation'.  The  con- 
centration of  attention  on  what  is  called  the  diffusion  of  culture- 
traits  tends  to  produce  a  conception  of  culture  as  a  collection  of 
disparate  entities  (the  so-called  traits)  brought  together  by  pure 
historical  accident  and  having  only  accidental  relations  to  one 
another.  The  conception  is  rarely  formulated  and  maintained  with 
any  precision,  but  as  a  half-unconscious  point  of  view  it  does 
seem  to  control  the  thinking  of  many  ethnologists.  It  is,  of 
course,  in  direct  conflict  with  the  hypothesis  of  the  functional 
unity  of  social  systems. 

The  second  view  which  is  in  direct  conflict  with  the  functional 
hypothesis  is  the  view  that  there  are  no  discoverable  significant 
sociological  laws  such  as  the  functionalist  is  seeking.  I  know  that 

^  I  see  no  reason  at  all  why  the  two  kinds  of  study — the  historical  and  the 
functional — should  not  be  carried  on  side  by  side  in  perfect  harmony.  In  fact, 
for  fourteen  years  I  have  been  teaching  both  the  historical  and  geographical 
study  of  peoples  under  the  name  of  ethnology  in  close  association  with  archae- 
ology, and  the  functional  study  of  social  systems  under  the  name  of  social 
anthropology.  I  do  think  that  there  are  many  disadvantages  in  mixing  the 
two  subjects  together  and  confusing  them.  See  'The  Methods  of  Ethnology 
and  Social  Anthropology'  {South  African  Journal  of  Science,  1923,  pp.  124-47). 

^  Primitive  Society,  p.  441.  A  concise  statement  of  this  point  of  view  is  the 
following  passage  from  Dr.  Ruth  Benedict's  'The  Concept  of  the  Guardian 
Spirit  in  North  America'  {Memoirs,  American  Anthropological  Association, 
29,  1923),  p.  84:  'It  is,  so  far  as  we  can  see,  an  ultimate  fact  of  human  nature 
that  man  builds  up  his  culture  out  of  disparate  elements,  combining  and  re- 
combining  them;  and  until  we  have  abandoned  the  superstition  that  the  result 
is  an  organism  functionally  interrelated,  we  shall  be  unable  to  see  our  cultural 
life  objectively,  or  to  control  its  manifestations.'  I  think  that  probably  neither 
Professor  Lowie  nor  Dr.  Benedict  would,  at  the  present  time,  maintain  this 
view  of  the  nature  of  culture. 


ON  THE  CONCEPT   OF   FUNCTION   IN   SOCIAL   SCIENCE         1 87 

some  two  or  three  ethnologists  say  that  they  hold  this  view,  but 
I  have  found  it  impossible  to  know  what  they  mean,  or  on  what 
sort  of  evidence  (rational  or  empirical)  they  would  base  their 
contention.  Generalisations  about  any  sort  of  subject  matter  are 
of  two  kinds:  the  generalisations  of  common  opinion,  and  generali- 
sations that  have  been  verified  or  demonstrated  by  a  systematic 
examination  of  evidence  afforded  by  precise  observations  sys- 
tematically made.  Generalisations  of  the  latter  kind  are  called 
scientific  laws.  Those  who  hold  that  there  are  no  laws  of  human 
society  cannot  hold  that  there  are  no  generalisations  about  human 
society  because  they  themselves  hold  such  generalisations  and 
even  make  new  ones  of  their  own.  They  must  therefore  hold  that 
in  the  field  of  social  phenomena,  in  contradistinction  to  physical 
and  biological  phenomena,  any  attempt  at  the  systematic  testing 
of  existing  generalisations  or  towards  the  discovery  and  veri- 
fication of  new  ones,  is,  for  some  unexplained  reason,  futile,  or, 
as  Dr.  Radin  puts  it,  'crying  for  the  moon'.  Argument  against  such 
a  contention  is  unprofitable  or  indeed  impossible. 


CHAPTER    X 

ON   SOCIAL   STRUCTURE! 

IT  has  been  suggested  to  me  by  some  of  my  friends  that  I 
should  use  this  occasion  to  offer  some  remarks  about  my 
own  point  of  view  in  social  anthropology;  and  since  in  my 
teaching,  beginning  at  Cambridge  and  at  the  London  School  of 
Economics  thirty  years  ago,  I  have  consistently  emphasised  the 
importance  of  the  study  of  social  structure,  the  suggestion  made  to 
me  was  that  I  should  say  something  on  that  subject. 

I  hope  you  will  pardon  me  if  I  begin  with  a  note  of  personal 
explanation.  I  have  been  described  on  more  than  one  occasion  as 
belonging  to  something  called  the  'Functional  School  of  Social 
Anthropology'  and  even  as  being  its  leader,  or  one  of  its  leaders. 
This  Functional  School  does  not  really  exist;  it  is  a  myth  invented 
by  Professor  Malinowski.  He  has  explained  how,  to  quote  his 
own  words,  'the  magnificent  title  of  the  Functional  School  of 
Anthropology  has  been  bestowed  by  myself,  in  a  way  on  myself, 
and  to  a  large  extent  out  of  my  own  sense  of  irresponsibility'. 
Professor  Malinowski's  irresponsibility  has  had  unfortunate 
results,  since  it  has  spread  over  anthropology  a  dense  fog  of 
discussion  about  'functionalism'.  Professor  Lowie  has  announced 
that  the  leading,  though  not  the  only,  exponent  of  functionalism 
in  the  nineteenth  century  was  Professor  Franz  Boas.  I  do  not 
think  that  there  is  any  sense,  other  than  the  purely  chronological 
one,  in  which  I  can  be  said  to  be  either  the  follower  of  Professor 
Boas  or  the  predecessor  of  Professor  Malinowski.  The  statement 
that  I  am  a  'functionalist'  would  seem  to  me  to  convey  no  definite 
meaning. 

There  is  no  place  in  natural  science  for  'schools'  in  this  sense, 
and  I  regard  social  anthropology  as  a  branch  of  natural  science. 
Each  scientist  starts  from  the  work  of  his  predecessors,  finds 
problems  which  he  believes  to  be  significant,  and  by  obser\'ation 
and  reasoning  endeavours  to  make  some  contribution  to  a  growing 
body  of  theory.  Co-operation  amongst  scientists  results  from  the 

^  Presidential  Address  to  the  Royal  Anthropological  Institute.  Reprinted 
from  the  Journal  of  the  Royal  Anthropological  Institute,  Vol.  LXX,  1940. 

188 


ON   SOCIAL  STRUCTURE  1 89 

fact  that  they  are  working  on  the  same  or  related  problems. 
Such  co-operation  does  not  result  in  the  formation  of  schools,  in 
the  sense  in  which  there  are  schools  of  philosophy  or  of  painting. 
There  is  no  place  for  orthodoxies  and  heterodoxies  in  science. 
Nothing  is  more  pernicious  in  science  than  attempts  to  establish 
adherence  to  doctrines.  All  that  a  teacher  can  do  is  to  assist  the, 
student  in  learning  to  understand  and  use  the  scientific  method. 
It  is  not  his  business  to  make  disciples. 

I  conceive  of  social  anthropology  as  the  theoretical  natural 
science  of  human  society,  that  is,  the  investigation  of  social 
phenomena  by  methods  essentially  similar  to  those  used  in 
the  physical  and  biological  sciences.  I  am  quite  willing  to  call  the 
subject  'comparative  sociolog)^',  if  anyone  so  wishes.  It  is  the 
subject  itself,  and  not  the  name,  that  is  important.  As  you  know, 
there  are  some  ethnologists  or  anthropologists  who  hold  that  it  is 
not  possible,  or  at  least  not  profitable,  to  apply  to  social  phenomena 
the  theoretical  methods  of  natural  science.  For  these  persons 
social  anthropology,  as  I  have  defined  it,  is  something  that  does 
not,  and  never  will,  exist.  For  them,  of  course,  my  remarks  will 
have  no  meaning,  or  at  least  not  the  meaning  I  intend  them  to 
have. 

While  I  have  defined  social  anthropology  as  the  study  of 
human  society,  there  are  some  who  define  it  as  the  study  of 
culture.  It  might  perhaps  be  thought  that  this  difference  of 
definition  is  of  minor  importance.  Actually  it  leads  to  two  different 
kinds  of  study,  between  which  it  is  hardly  possible  to  obtain 
agreement  in  the  formulation  of  problems. 

For  a  preliminary  definition  of  social  phenomena  it  seems 
sufficiently  clear  that  what  we  have  to  deal  with  are  relations  of 
association  between  individual  organisms.  In  a  hive  of  bees 
there  are  the  relations  of  association  of  the  queen,  the  workers 
and  the  drones.  There  is  the  association  of  animals  in  a  herd,  of 
a  mother-cat  and  her  kittens.  These  are  social  phenomena; 
I  do  not  suppose  that  anyone  will  call  them  cultural  phenomena. 
In  anthropology,  of  course,  we  are  only  concerned  with  human 
beings,  and  in  social  anthropology,  as  I  define  it,  what  we  have 
to  investigate  are  the  forms  of  association  to  be  found  amongst 
human  beings. 

Let  us  consider  what  are  the  concrete,  observable  facts  with 
which  the  social  anthropologist  is  concerned.  If  we  set  out  to  study. 


190  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN    PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

for  example,  the  aboriginal  inhabitants  of  a  part  of  Australia,  we 
find  a  certain  number  of  individual  human  beings  in  a  certain 
natural  environment.  We  can  observe  the  acts  of  behaviour  of 
tfiese   individuals,   including,   of  course,   their  acts   of  speech, 
/and  the  material  products  of  past  actions.  We  do  not  observe  a 
/    'culture',  since  that  word  denotes,  not  any  concrete  reality,  but 
an  abstraction,  and  as  it  is  commonly  used  a  vague  abstraction. 
But  direct  observation  does  reveal  to  us  that  these  human  beings 
/are  connected  by  a  complex  network  of  social  relations.  I  use  the 
Wrm  'social  structure'  to  denote  this  network  of  actually  existing 
relations.  It  is  this  that  I  regard  it  as  my  business  to  study  if  I 
"Xam  working,  not  as  an  ethnologist  or  psychologist,  but  as  a  social 
anthropologist.  I  do  not  mean  that  the  study  of  social  structure  is 
the  whole  of  social  anthropology,  but  I  do  regard  it  as  being  in 
a  very  important  sense  the  most  fundamental  part  of  the  science. 
My  view  of  natural  science  is  that  it  is  the  systematic  investiga- 
tion of  the  structure  of  the  universe  as  it  is  revealed  to  us  through 
our  senses.  There  are  certain  important  separate  branches  of  science, 
each  of  which  deals  with  a  certain  class  or  kind  of  structures,  the 
aim  being  to  discover  the  characteristics  of  all  structures  of  that  kind. 
So  atomic  physics  deals  with  the  structure  of  atoms,  chemistry  with 
the  structure  of  molecules,  crystallography  and  colloidal  chemistry 
with  the  structure  of  crystals  and  colloids,  and  anatomy  and 
physiology  with  the  structures  of  organisms.  There  is,  therefore, 
I  suggest,  place  for  a  branch  of  natural  science  which  will  have 
for  its  task  the  discovery  of  the  general  characteristics  of  those 
social  structures  of  which  the  component  units  are  human  beings. 
Social    phenomena    constitute    a    distinct    class    of    natural 
phenomena.  They  are  all,  in  one  way  or  another,  connected 
with  the  existence  of  social  structures,  either  being  implied  in  or 
resulting  from  them.   Social  structures  are  just  as  real  as  are 
individual   organisms.   A  complex  organism   is   a   collection   of 
living  cells  and  interstitial  fluids  arranged  in  a  certain  structure; 
and  a  living  cell  is  similarly  a  structural  arrangement  of  complex 
molecules.  The  physiological  and  psychological  phenomena  that 
we  observe  in  the  lives  of  organisms  are  not  simply  the  result  of  the 
nature  of  the  constituent  molecules  or  atoms  of  which  the  organism 
is  built  up,  but  are  the  result  of  the  structure  in  which  they  are 
united.  So  also  the  social  phenomena  which  we  observe  in  any 
human  society  are  not  the  immediate  result  of  the  nature  of 


ON  SOCIAL  STRUCTURE  191 

individual  human  beings,  but  are  tlie  result  of  the  social  structure 
by  which  they  are  united. 

It  should  be  noted  that  to  say  we  are  studying  social  structures 
is  not  exactly  the  same  thing  as  saying  that  we  study  social  relations, 
which  is  how  some  sociologists  define  their  subject.  A  particular 
social  relation  between  two  persons  (unless  they  be  Adam  and 
Eve  in  the  Garden  of  Eden)  exists  only  as  part  of  a  wide  network 
of  social  relations,  involving  many  other  persons,  and  it  is  this 
network  which  I  regard  as  the  object  of  our  investigations. 

I  am  aware,  of  course,  that  the  term  'social  structure'  is  used 
in  a  number  of  different  senses,  some  of  them  very  vague.  This 
is  unfortunately  true  of  many  otlier  terms  commonly  used  by 
anthropologists.  The  choice  of  terms  and  their  definitions  is  a 
matter  of  scientific  convenience,  but  one  of  the  characteristics  of  a 
science  as  soon  as  it  has  passed  the  first  formative  period  is  the 
existence  of  technical  terms  which  are  used  in  the  same  precise 
meaning  by  all  the  students  of  that  science.  By  this  test,  I  regret 
to  say,  social  anthropology  reveals  itself  as  not  yet  a  formed 
science.  One  has  therefore  to  select  for  oneself,  for  certain  terms, 
definitions  which  seem  to  be  the  most  convenient  for  the  purpose 
of  scientific  analysis. 

There  are  some  anthropologists  who  use  the  term  social 
structure  to  refer  only  to  persistent  social  groups,  such  as  nations, 
tribes  and  clans,  which  retain  their  continuity,  their  identity 
as  individual  groups,  in  spite  of  changes  in  their  membership. 
Dr.  Evans-Pritchard,  in  his  recent  admirable  book  on  the  Nuer, 
prefers  to  use  the  term  social  structure  in  this  sense.  Certainly 
the  existence  of  such  persistent  social  groups  is  an  exceedingly 
important  aspect  of  structure.  But  I  find  it  more  useful  to  include 
under  the  term  social  structure  a  good  deal  more  than  this. 

In  the  first  place,  I  regard  as  a  part  of  the  social  structure  all 
social  relations  of  person  to  person.  For  example,  the  kinship 
structure  of  any  society  consists  of  a  number  of  such  dyadic 
relations,  as  between  a  father  and  son,  or  a  mother's  brother  and 
his  sister's  son.  In  an  Australian  tribe  the  whole  social  structure 
is  based  on  a  network  of  such  relations  of  person  to  person, 
established  through  genealogical  connections. 

Secondly,  I  include  under  social  structure  the  differentiation 
of  individuals  and  of  classes  by  their  social  role.  The  differential 
social  positions  of  men  and  women,  of  chiefs  and  commoners, 


192  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

of  employers  and  employees,  are  just  as  much  determinants  of 
social  relations  as  belonging  to  different  clans  or  different  nations. 

In  the  study  of  social  structure  the  concrete  reality  with  which 
we  are  concerned  is  the  set  of  actually  existing  relations,  at  a  given 
moment  of  time,  which  link  together  certain  human  beings. 
It  is  on  this  that  we  can  make  direct  observations.  But  it  is  not 
this  that  we  attempt  to  describe  in  its  particularity.  Science 
(as  distinguished  from  history  or  biography)  is  not  concerned 
with  the  particular,  the  unique,  but  only  with  the  general,  with 
kinds,  with  events  which  recur.  The  actual  relations  of  Tom, 
Dick  and  Harry  or  the  behaviour  of  Jack  and  Jill  may  go  down  in 
our  field  note-books  and  may  provide  illustrations  for  a  general 
description.  But  what  we  need  for  scientific  purposes  is  an  account 
of  the  form  of  the  structure.  For  example,  if  in  an  Australian 
tribe  I  observe  in  a  number  of  instances  the  behaviour  towards 
one  another  of  persons  who  stand  in  the  relation  of  mother's 
brother  and  sister's  son,  it  is  in  order  that  I  may  be  able  to 
record  as  precisely  as  possible  the  general  or  normal  form  of  this 
relationship,  abstracted  from-  the  variations  of  particular  instances, 
though  taking  account  of  those  variations. 

This  important  distinction,  between  structure  as  an  actually 
existing  concrete  reality,  to  be  directly  observed,  and  structural 
form,  as  what  the  field-worker  describes,  may  be  made  clearer 
perhaps  by  a  consideration  of  the  continuity  of  social  structure 
through  time,  a  continuity  which  is  not  static  like  that  of  a  hjiilding, 
but  a  dynamic  continuity,  like  that  of  the  organic  structure  of  a 
living  body.  Throughout  the  life  of  an  organism  its  structure  is 
being  constantly  renewed;  and  similarly  the  social  life  constantly 
renews  the  social  structure.  Thus  the  actual  relations  of  persons 
and  groups  of  persons  change  from  year  to  year,  or  even  from  day 
to  day.  New  members  come  into  a  community  by  birth  or  im- 
migration; others  go  out  of  it  by  death  or  emigration.  There  are 
marriages  and  divorces.  Friends  may  become  enemies,  or  enemies 
may  make  peace  and  become  friends.  But  while  the  actual  structure 
changes  in  this  way,  the  general  structural  form  may  remain 
relatively  constant  over  a  longer  or  shorter  period  of  time.  Thus 
if  I  visit  a  relatively  stable  community  and  revisit  it  after  an  interval 
of  ten  years,  I  shall  find  that  many  of  its  members  have  died  and 
others  have  been  born;  the  members  who  still  survive  are  now  ten 
years  older  and  their  relations  to  one  another  may  have  changed 


ON   SOCIAL   STRUCTURE  1 93 

in  many  ways.  Yet  I  may  find  that  the  kinds  of  relations  that  I 
can  observe  are  very  little  different  from  those  observed  ten  years 
before.  The  structural  form  has  changed  little. 

But,  on  the  other  hand,  the  structural  form  may  change, 
sometimes  gradually,  sometimes  with  relative  suddenness,  as  in 
revolutions  and  military  conquests.  But  even  in  the  most  revolu- 
tionary changes  some  continuity  of  structure  is  maintained. 

I  must  say  a  few  words  about  the  spatial  aspect  of  social 
structure.  It  is  rarely  that  we  find  a  community  that  is  absolutely 
isolated,  having  no  outside  contact.  At  the  present  moment  of 
history,  the  network  of  social  relations  spreads  over  the  whole 
world,  without  any  absolute  solution  of  continuity  anywhere. 
This  gives  rise  to  a  difficulty  which  I  do  not  think  that  sociologists 
have  really  faced,  the  difficulty  of  defining  what  is  meant  by  the 
term  'a  society'.  They  do  commonly  talk  of  societies  as  if  they 
were  distinguishable,  discrete  entities,  as,  for  example,  when  we 
are  told  that  a  society  is  an  organism.  Is  the  British  Empire  a 
society  or  a  collection  of  societies?  Is  a  Chinese  village  a  society, 
or  is  it  merely  a  fragment  of  the  Republic  of  China? 

If  we  say  that  our  subject  is  the  study  and  comparison  of 
human  societies,  we  ought  to  be  able  to  say  what  are  the  unit 
entities  with  which  we  are  concerned. 

If  we  take  any  convenient  locality  of  a  suitable  size,  we  can 
study  the  structural  system  as  it  appears  in  and  from  that  region, 
i.e.  the  network  of  relations  connecting  the  inhabitants  amongst 
themselves  and  with  the  people  of  other  regions.  We  can  thus 
observe,  describe,  and  compare  the  systems  of  social  structure  of 
as  many  localities  as  we  wish.  To  illustrate  what  I  mean,  I  may 
refer  to  two  recent  studies  from  the  University  of  Chicago,  one 
of  a  Japanese  village,  Suye  Mura,  by  Dr.  John  Embree,  and  the 
other  of  a  French  Canadian  community,  St.  Denis,  by  Dr. 
Horace  Miner. 

Closely  connected  with  this  conception  of  social  structure 
is  the  conception  of  'social  personality'  as  the  position  occupied 
by  a  human  being  in  a  social  structure,  the  complex  formed  by 
all  his  social  relations  with  others.  Every  human  being  living  in 
society  is  two  things:  he  is  an  individual  and  also  a  person.  As  an 
individual,  he  is  a  biological  organism,  a  collection  of  a  vast  number 
of  molecules  organised  in  a  complex  structure,  within  which, 
as  long  as  it  persists,  there  occur  physiological  and  psychological 

7 


194  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

actions  and  reactions,  processes  and  changes.  Human  beings 
as  individuals  are  objects  of  study  for  physiologists  and  psycho- 
logists. The  human  being  as  a  person  is  a  complex  of  social 
relationships.  He  is  a  citizen  of  England,  a  husband  and  a  father, 
a  bricklayer,  a  member  of  a  particular  Methodist  congregation, 
a  voter  in  a  certain  constituency,  a  member  of  his  trade  union,  an 
adherent  of  the  Labour  Party,  and  so  on.  Note  that  each  of  these 
descriptions  refers  to  a  social  relationship,  or  to  a  place  in  a  social 
structure.  Note  also  that  a  social  personality  is  something  that 
changes  during  the  course  of  the  life  of  the  person.  As  a  person, 
the  human  being  is  the  object  of  study  for  the  social  anthropologist. 
We  cannot  study  persons  except  in  terms  of  social  structure,  nor 
can  we  study  social  structure  except  in  terms  of  the  persons  who 
are  the  units  of  which  it  is  composed. 

If  you  tell  me  that  an  individual  and  a  person  are  after  all 
really  the  same  thing,  I  would  remind  you  of  the  Christian  creed. 
God  is  three  persons,  but  to  say  that  He  is  three  individuals 
is  to  be  guilty  of  a  heresy  for  which  men  have  been  put  to  death. 
Yet  the  failure  to  distinguish  individual  and  person  is  not  merely 
a  heresy  in  religion;  it  is  worse  than  that;  it  is  a  source  of  confusion 
in  science. 

I  have  now  sufficiently  defined,  I  hope,  the  subject-matter 
of  what  I  regard  as  an  extremely  important  branch  of  social 
anthropology.  The  method  to  be  adopted  follows  immediately 
from  this  definition.  It  must  combine  with  the  intensive  study  of 
single  societies  (i.e.  of  the  structural  systems  observable  in  par- 
ticular communities)  the  systematic  comparison  of  many  societies 
(or  structural  systems  of  different  types).  The  use  of  comparison 
is  indispensable.  The  study  of  a  single  society  may  provide 
materials  for  comparative  study,  or  it  may  afford  occasion  for 
hypotheses,  which  then  need  to  be  tested  by  reference  to  other 
societies;   it  cannot  give  demonstrated  results. 

Our  first  task,  of  course,  is  to  learn  as  much  as  we  can  about 
the  varieties,  or  diversities,  of  structural  systems.  This  requires 
field  research.  Many  writers  of  ethnographical  descriptions  do  not 
attempt  to  give  us  any  systematic  account  of  the  social  structure. 
But  a  few  social  anthropologists,  here  and  in  America,  do  recognise 
the  importance  of  such  data  and  their  work  is  providing  us  with  a 
steadily  growing  body  of  material  for  our  study.  Moreover,  their 
researches  are  no  longer  confined  to  what  are  called  'primitive' 


ON   SOCIAL   STRUCTURE  1 95 

societies,  but  extend  to  communities  in  such  regions  as  Sicily, 
Ireland,  Japan,  Canada  and  the  United  States. 

If  we  are  to  have  a  real  comparative  morphology  of  societies, 
however,  we  must  aim  at  building  up  some  sort  of  classification  of 
types  of  structural  systems.  That  is  a  complex  and  difficult  task, 
to  which  I  have  myself  devoted  attention  for  thirty  years.  It  is  the 
kind  of  task  that  needs  the  co-operation  of  a  number  of  students 
and  I  think  I  can  number  on  my  fingers  those  who  are  actively 
interested  in  it  at  the  present  time.  Nevertheless,  I  believe  some 
progress  is  being  made.  Such  work,  however,  does  not  produce 
spectacular  results  and  a  book  on  the  subject  would  certainly 
not  be  an  anthropological  best-seller. 

We  should  remember  that  chemistry  and  biology  did  not 
become  fully  formed  sciences  until  considerable  progress  had  been 
made  with  the  systematic  classification  of  the  things  they  were 
dealing  with,  substances  in  the  one  instance  and  plants  and  animals 
in  the  other. 

Besides  this  morphological  study,  consisting  in  the  definition, 
comparison  and  classification  of  diverse  structural  systems,  there 
is  a  physiological  study.  The  problem  here  is:  How  do  structural 
systems  persist?  What  are  the  mechanisms  which  maintain  a 
network  of  social  relations  in  existence,  and  how  do  they  work? 
In  using  the  terms  morphology  and  physiology,  I  may  seem  to  be 
returning  to  the  analogy  between  society  and  organism  which  was 
so  popular  with  medieval  philosophers,  was  taken  over  and  often 
misused  by  nineteenth  century  sociologists,  and  is  completely 
rejected  by  many  modern  writers.  But  analogies,  properly  used, 
are  important  aids  to  scientific  thinking  and  there  is  a  real  and 
significant  analogy  between  organic  structure  and  social  structure. 

In  what  I  am  thus  calling  social  physiology  we  are  concerned 
not  only  with  social  structure,  but  with  every  kind  of  social 
phenomenon.  Morals,  law,  etiquette,  religion,  government,  and 
education  are  all  parts  of  the  complex  mechanism  by  which  a 
social  structure  exists  and  persists.  If  we  take  up  the  structural 
point  of  view,  we  study  these  things,  not  in  abstraction  or  isolation, 
but  in  their  direct  and  indirect  relations  to  social  structure,  i.e. 
with  reference  to  the  way  in  which  they  depend  upon,  or  affect, 
the  social  relations  between  persons  and  groups  of  persons. 
I  cannot  do  more  here  than  offer  a  few  brief  illustrations  of  \\  hat 
this  means. 


196  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

Let  US  first  consider  the  study  of  language.  A  language  is  a 
connected  set  of  speech  usages  observed  within  a  defined  speech- 
community.  The  existence  of  speech-communities  and  their 
sizes  are  features  of  social  structure.  There  is,  therefore,  a  certain 
very  general  relation  between  social  structure  and  language.  But 
if  we  consider  the  special  characteristics  of  a  particular  language — 
its  phonology,  its  morphology  and  even  to  a  great  extent  its 
vocabulary — there  is  no  direct  connection  of  either  one-sided 
or  mutual  determination  between  these  and  the  special  charac- 
teristics of  the  social  structure  of  the  community  within  which  the 
language  is  spoken.  We  can  easily  conceive  that  two  societies 
might  have  very  similar  forms  of  social  structure  and  very  different 
kinds  of  language,  or  vice  versa.  The  coincidence  of  a  particular 
form  of  social  structure  and  a  particular  language  in  a  given 
community  is  always  the  result  of  historical  accident.  There  may, 
of  course,  be  certain  indirect,  remote  interactions  between  social 
structure  and  language,  but  these  would  seem  to  be  of  minor 
importance.  Thus  the  general  comparative  study  of  languages 
can  be  profitably  carried  out  as  a  relatively  independent  branch 
of  science,  in  which  the  language  is  considered  in  abstraction 
from  the  social  structure  of  the  community  in  which  it  is  spoken. 

But,  on  the  other  hand,  there  are  certain  features  of  linguistic 
history  which  are  specifically  connected  with  social  structure. 
As  structural  phenomena  may  be  instanced  the  process  by  which 
Latin,  from  being  the  language  of  the  small  region  of  Latium, 
became  the  language  of  a  considerable  part  of  Europe,  displacing 
the  other  Italic  languages,  Etruscan,  and  many  Celtic  languages; 
and  the  subsequent  reverse  process  by  which  Latin  split  up  into 
a  number  of  diverse  local  forms  of  speech,  which  ultimately 
became  the  various  Romance  languages  of  today. 

Thus  the  spread  of  language,  the  unification  of  a  number  of 
separate  communities  into  a  single  speech-community,  and  the 
reverse  process  of  subdivision  into  different  speech-communities, 
are  phenomena  of  social  structure.  So  also  are  those  instances  in 
which,  in  societies  having  a  class  structure,  there  are  differences 
.of  speech  usage  in  different  classes. 

I  have  considered  language  first,  because  linguistics  is,  I 
think,  the  branch  of  social  anthropology  which  can  be  most 
profitably  studied  without  reference  to  social  structure.  There  is  a 
reason  for  this.  The  set  of  speech  usages  which  constitute  a 


ON   SOCIAL   STRUCTURE  1 97 

language  does  form  a  system,  and  systems  of  this  kind  can  be 
compared  in  order  to  discover  their  common  general,  or  abstract, 
characters,  the  determination  of  which  can  give  us  laws,  which  will 
be  specifically  laws  of  linguistics. 

Let  us  consider  very  briefly  certain  other  branches  of  social 
anthropology  and  their  relation  to  the  study  of  social  structure. 
If  we  take  the  social  life  of  a  local  community  over  a  period,  let  us 
say  a  year,  we  can  observe  a  certain  sum  total  of  activities  carried 
out  by  the  persons  who  compose  it.  We  can  also  observe  a  certain 
apportionment  of  these  activities,  one  person  doing  certain  things, 
another  doing  others.  This  apportionment  of  activities,  equivalent 
to  what  is  sometimes  called  the  social  division  of  labour,  is  an 
important  feature  of  the  social  structure.  Now  activities  are  carried 
out  because  they  provide  some  sort  of  '  gratification  ',  as  I  propose 
to  call  it,  and  the  characteristic  feature  of  social  life  is  that 
activities  of  certain  persons  provide  gratifications  for  other 
persons.  In  a  simple  instance,  when  an  Australian  blackfcllow 
goes  hunting,  he  provides  meat,  not  only  for  himself,  but  for 
his  wife  and  children  and  also  for  other  relatives  to  whom  it  is 
his  duty  to  give  meat  when  he  has  it.  Thus  in  any  society  there 
is  not  only  an  apportionment  of  activities,  but  also  an  apportion- 
ment of  the  gratifications  resulting  therefrom,  and  some  sort  of 
social  machinery,  relatively  simple  or,  sometimes,  highly  complex, 
by  which  the  system  works. 

It  is  this  machinery,  or  certain  aspects  of  it,  that  constitutes 
the  special  subject-matter  studied  by  the  economists.  They  con- 
cern themselves  with  what  kinds  and  quantities  of  goods  are 
produced,  how  they  are  distributed  (i.e.  their  flow  from  person 
to  person,  or  region  to  region),  and  the  way  in  which  they  are 
disposed  oL  Thus  what  are  called  economic  institutions  are 
extensively  studied  in  more  or  less  complete  abstraction  from  the 
rest  of  the  social  system.  This  method  does  undoubtedly  provide 
useful  results,  particularly  in  the  study  of  complex  modern 
societies.  Its  weaknesses  become  apparent  as  soon  as  we  attempt 
to  apply  it  to  the  exchange  of  goods  in  what  are  called  primitive 
societies. 

The  economic  machinery  of  a  society  appears  in  quite  a  new 
light  if  it  is  studied  in  relation  to  the  social  structure.  The  exchange 
of  goods  and  services  is  dependent  upon,  is  the  result  of,  and  at 
the  same  time  is  a  means  of  maintaining  a  certain  structure,  a 


198  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN  PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

network  of  relations  between  persons  and  collections  of  persons. 
For  the  economists  and  politicians  of  Canada  the  potlatch  of  the 
Indians  of  the  north-west  of  America  was  simply  wasteful  foolish- 
ness and  it  was  therefore  forbidden.  For  the  anthropologist  it 
was  the  machinery  for  maintaining  a  social  structure  of  lineages, 
clans  and  moieties,  with  which  was  combined  an  arrangement  of 
rank  defined  by  privileges. 

Any  full  understanding  of  the  economic  institutions  of  human 
societies  requires  that  they  should  be  studied  from  two  angles. 
From  one  of  these  the  economic  system  is  viewed  as  the  mechanism 
by  which  goods  of  various  kinds  and  in  various  quantities  are 
produced,  transported  and  transferred,  and  utilised.  From  the 
other  the  economic  system  is  a  set  of  relations  between  persons  and 
groups  which  maintains^  and  is  maintained  by,  this  exchange  or 
circulation  of  goods  and  services.  From  the  latter  point  of  view, 
the  study  of  the  economic  life  of  societies  takes  its  place  as  part 
of  the  general  study  of  social  structure. 

Social  relations  are  only  observed,  and  can  only  be  described, 
by  reference  to  the  reciprocal  behaviour  of  the  persons  related. 
The  form  of  a  social  structure  has  therefore  to  be  described  by 
the  patterns  of  behaviour  to  which  individuals  and  groups  con- 
form in  their  dealings  with  one  another.  These  patterns  are 
partially  formulated  in  rules  which,  in  our  own  society,  we  dis- 
tinguish as  rules  of  etiquette,  of  morals  and  of  law.  Rules,  of  course, 
only  exist  in  their  recognition  by  the  members  of  the  society; 
either  in  their  verbal  recognition,  when  they  are  stated  as  rules, 
or  in  their  observance  in  behaviour.  These  two  modes  of  re- 
cognition, as  every  field-worker  knows,  are  not  the  same  thing  and 
both  have  to  be  taken  into  account. 

If  I  say  that  in  any  society  the  rules  of  etiquette,  morals  and 
law  are  part  of  the  mechanism  by  which  a  certain  set  of  social 
relations  is  maintained  in  existence,  this  statement  will,  I  suppose, 
be  greeted  as  a  truism.  But  it  is  one  of  those  truisms  which  many 
writers  on  human  society  verbally  accept  and  yet  ignore  in 
theoretical  discussions,  or  in  their  descriptive  analyses.  The 
point  is  not  that  rules  exist  in  every  society,  but  that  what  we  need 
to  know  for  a  scientific  understanding  is  just  how  these  things 
work  in  general  and  in  particular  instances. 

Let  us  consider,  for  example,  the  study  of  law.  If  you  examine 
the  literature  on  jurisprudence  you  will  find  that  legal  institutions 


ON   SOCIAL   STRUCTURE  1 99 

are  studied  for  the  most  part  in  more  or  less  complete  abstraction 
from  the  rest  of  the  social  system  of  which  they  are  a  part.  This 
is  doubtless  the  most  convenient  method  for  la\\'yers  in  their 
professional  studies.  But  for  any  scientific  investigation  of  the 

•  nature  of  law  it  is  insufficient.  The  data  with  which  a  scientist 
must  deal  are  events  which  occur  and  can  be  observed.  In  the 
field  of  law,  the  events  which  the  social  scientist  can  observe  and 
thus  take  as  his  data  are  the  proceedings  that  take  place  in  courts 
of  justice.  These  are  the  reality,  and  for  the  social  anthropologist 
they  are  the  mechanism  or  process  by  which  certain  definable 
social  relations  between  persons  and  groups  are  restored,  main- 
tained or  modified.  Law  is  a  part  of  the  machinery  by  which  a       ' 
certain  social  structure  is  maintained.  The  system  of  laws  of  a 
particular  society  can  only  be  fully  understood  if  it  is  studied     j 
in  relation  to  the  social  structure,  and  inversely  the  understanding 
of  the  social  structure  requires,  amongst  other  things,  a  systematic     I 
study  of  the  legal  institutions.  — ^ 

I  have  talked  about  social  relations,  but  I  have  not  so  far 
offered  you  a  precise  definition.  A  social  relation  exists  between 
two  or  more  individual  organisms  when  there  is  some  adjustment 
of  their  respective  interests,  by  convergence  of  interest,  or  by 

\,  limitation  of  conflicts  that  might  arise  from  divergence  of  interests. 
I  use  the  term  'interest'  here  in  the  widest  possible  sense,  to 
refer  to  all  behaviour  that  we  regard  as  purposive.  To  speak  of  an 
interest  implies  a  subject  and  an  object  and  a  relation  between 
them.  Whenever  we  say  that  a  subject  has  a  certain  interest  in  an 

,  object  we  can  state  the  same  thing  by  saying  that  the  object  has 
a  certain  value  for  the  subject.  Interest  and  value  are  correlative  "] 
terms,  which  refer  to  the  two  sides  of  an  asymmetrical  relation.      -J 

Thus  the  study  of  social  structure  leads  immediately  to  the 
study  of  interests  or  values  as  the  determinants  of  social  relations. 
A  social  relation  does  not  result  from  similarity  of  interests,  but^^ 
rests  either  on  the  mutual  interest  of  persons  in  one  another,  or 
on  one  or  more  common  interests,  or  on  a  combination  of  both 
of  these.  The  simplest  form  of  social  solidarity  is  where  two 
persons  are  both  interested  in  bringing  about  a  certain  result  and 
co-operate  to  that  end.  When  two  or  more  persons  have  a  common— y 
interest  in  an  object,  that  object  can  be  said  to  have  a  social  ralue 
for  the    persons   thus   associated.    If,   then,   practically   all   the  ^ 
members  of  a  society  have  an  interest  in  the  obscr\'ance  of  the 


200  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

I     ^laws,  we  can  say  that  the  law  has  a  social  value.  The  study  of 
social  values  in  this  sense  is  therefore  a  part  of  the  study  of  social 
^    structure. 

It  was  from  this  point  of  view  that  in  an  early  work  I  approached 
the  study  of  what  can  conveniently  be  called  ritual  values,  i.e.  the 
values  expressed  in  rites  and  myths.  It  is  perhaps  again  a  truism 
to  say  that  religion  is  the  cement  which  holds  society  together. 
But  for  a  scientific  understanding  we  need  to  know  just  how  it 
does  this,  and  that  is  a  subject  for  lengthy  investigations  in  many 
different  forms  of  society. 

As  a  last  example  let  me  mention  the  study  of  magic  and 
witchcraft,  on  which  there  is  an  extensive  anthropological 
literature.  I  would  point  to  Dr.  Evans-Pritchard's  work  on  the 
Zande  as  an  illuminating  example  of  what  can  be  done  when  these 
things  are  systematically  investigated  in  terms  of  the  part  they 
play  in  the  social  relations  of  the  members  of  a  community. 

From  the  point  of  view  that  I  have  attempted  briefly  to  de- 
scribe, social  institutions,  in  the  sense  of  standardised  modes  of 
behaviour,  constitute  the  machinery  by  which  a  social  structure, 
a  network  of  social  relations,  maintains  its  existence  and   its 
continuity.  I  hesitate  to  use  the  term  'function',  which  in  recent 
years  has  been  so  much  used   and  misused  in  a  multitude  of 
meanings,  many  of  them  very  vague.  Instead  of  being  used,  as 
scientific  terms  ought  to  be,  to  assist  in  making  distinctions,  it  is 
now  used  to  confuse  things  that  ought  to  be  distinguished.  For  it 
is  often  employed  in  place  of  the  more  ordinary  words    'use' 
'purpose',  and  'meaning'.  It  seems  to  me  more  convenient  and 
sensible,  as  well  as  more  scholarly,  to  speak  of  the  use  or  uses 
of  an  axe  or  digging  stick,  the  meaning  of  a  word  or  symbol,  the 
purpose  of  an  act  of  legislation,  rather  than  to  use  the  word 
function  for  these  various  things.  'Function'  has  been  a  very 
useful  technical  term  in  physiology  and  by  analogy  with  its  use 
in  that  science  it  would  be  a  very  convenient  means  of  expressing 
an  important  concept  in  social  science.  As  I  have  been  accustomed 
to  use  the  word,  following  Durkheim  and  others,  I  would  define 
-     the  social  function  of  a  socially  standardised  mode  of  activity,  or 
f     mode  of  thought,  as  its  relation  to  the  social  structure  to  the 
existence  and  continuity  of  which  it  makes  some  contribution. 
Analogously,  in  a  living  organism,  the  physiological  function  of 
the  beating  of  the  heart,  or  the  secretion  of  gastric  juices,  is  its 


ON   SOCIAL  STRUCTURE  201 

relation  to  the  organic  structure  to  the  existence  or  continuity  of 
which  it  makes  its  contribution.  It  is  in  this  sense  that  I  am  inter- 
ested in  such  things  as  the  social  function  of  the  punishment  of 
crime,  or  the  social  function  of  the  totemic  rites  of  Australian 
tribes,  or  of  the  funeral  rites  of  the  Andaman  Islanders.  But 
this  is  not  what  either  Professor  Malinowski  or  Professor  Lowie 
means  by  functional  anthropology. 

Besides  these  two  divisions  of  the  study  of  social  structure, 
which  I  have  called  social  morphology  and  social  physiology, 
there  is  a  third,  the  investigation  of  the  processes  by  which  social 
structures  change,  of  how  new  forms  of  structures  come  into 
existence.  Studies  of  social  change  in  the  non-literate  societies 
have  necessarily  been  almost  entirely  confined  to  one  special 
kind  of  process  of  change,  the  modification  of  the  social  life  under 
the  influence  or  domination  of  European  invaders  or  conquerors. 

It  has  recently  become  the  fashion  amongst  some  anthropo- 
logists to  treat  changes  of  this  kind  in  terms  of  what  is  called 
'culture  contact'.  By  that  term  we  can  understand  the  one-sided 
or  two-sided  effects  of  interaction  between  two  societies,  groups, 
classes  or  regions  having  different  forms  of  social  life,  different 
institutions,  usages  and  ideas.  Thus  in  the  eighteenth  century 
there  was  an  important  exchange  of  ideas  between  France  and 
Great  Britain,  and  in  the  nineteenth  century  there  was  a  marked 
influence  of  German  thought  on  both  France  and  England. 
Such  interactions  are,  of  course,  a  constant  feature  of  social  life, 
but  they  need  not  necessarily  involve  any  marked  change  of 
social  structure. 

The  changes  that  are  taking  place  in  the  non-literate  peoples 
of  Africa  are  of  a  very  different  kind.  Let  us  consider  an  African 
colony  or  possession  of  a  European  nation.  There  is  a  region 
that  was  formerly  inhabited  by  Africans  with  their  own  social  struc- 
ture. Europeans,  by  peaceful  or  forceful  means,  establish  control 
over  the  region,  under  what  we  call  a  'colonial'  regime.  A  new 
social  structure  comes  into  existence  and  then  undergoes  develop- 
ment. The  population  now  includes  a  certain  number  of  Europeans 
— government  officials,  missionaries,  traders  and  in  some  in- 
stances settlers.  The  social  life  of  the  region  is  no  longer  simply 
a  process  depending  on  the  relations  and  interactions  of  the 
native  peoples.  There  grows  up  a  new  political  and  economic 
structure  in  which  the  Europeans,  even  though  few  in  numbers, 


202  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

exercise  dominating  influence.  Europeans  and  Africans  constitute 
different  classes  within  the  new  structure,  with  different  languages, 
different  customs  and  modes  of  life,  and  different  sets  of  ideas  and 
values.  A  convenient  term  for  societies  of  this  kind  would  be 
'composite'  societies;  the  term  'plural'  societies  has  also  been 
suggested.  A  complex  example  of  a  composite  society  is  provided 
by  the  Union  of  South  Africa  w4th  its  single  political  and  eco- 
nomic structure  and  a  population  including  English-speaking 
and  Afrikaans-speaking  peoples  of  European  descent,  the  so-called 
'coloured  people'  of  the  Cape  Province,  progeny  of  Dutch  and 
Hottentots,  the  remaining  Hottentots,  the  'Malays'  of  Cape 
Town,  descendants  of  persons  from  the  Malay  Archipelago,  Hindus 
and  Mohammedans  from  India  and  their  descendants,  and  a 
number  of  Bantu  tribes  who  constitute  the  majority  of  the 
population  of  the  Union  taken  as  a  whole. 

The  study  of  composite  societies,  the  description  and  analysis 
of  the  processes  of  change  in  them,  is  a  complex  and  difficult 
task.  The  attempt  to  simplify  it  by  considering  the  process  as 
being  one  in  which  two  or  more  'cultures'  interact,  which  is  the 
method  suggested  by  Malinowski  in  his  Introduction  to  Memoran- 
dum XV  of  the  International  Institute  of  African  Language 
and  Culture  on  'Methods  of  Study  of  Culture  Contact  in  Africa' 
(1938),  is  simply  a  way  of  avoiding  the  reality.  For  what  is 
happening  in  South  Africa,  for  example,  is  not  the  interaction 
of  British  culture,  Afrikander  (or  Boer)  culture,  Hottentot  cultures- 
various  Bantu  cultures  and  Indian  culture,  but  the  interaction 
of  individuals  and  groups  within  an  established  social  structure 
which  is  itself  in  process  of  change.  What  is  happening  in  a 
Transkeian  tribe,  for  example,  can  only  be  described  by  recognising 
that  the  tribe  has  been  incorporated  into  a  wide  political  and 
economic  structural  system. 

For  the  scientific  study  of  primitive  societies  in  conditions  in 
which  they  are  free  from  the  domination  by  more  advanced 
societies  which  result  in  these  composite  societies,  we  have 
unfortunately  an  almost  complete  lack  of  authentic  historical 
data.  We  cannot  study,  but  can  only  speculate  about,  the  processes 
of  change  that  took  place  in  the  past  of  which  we  have  no  record. 
Anthropologists  speculate  about  former  changes  in  the  societies 
of  the  Australian  aborigines,  or  the  inhabitants  of  Melanesia, 
but  such  speculations  are  not  history  and  can  be  of  no  use  in 


ON   SOCIAL   STRUCTURE  203 

science.  For  the  study  of  social  change  in  societies  other  than  the 
composite  societies  to  which  reference  has  been  made  we  have 
to  rely  on  the  work  of  historians  dealing  with  authentic  records. 

You  are  aware  that  in  certain  anthropological  circles  the  term 
'evolutionary  anthropologist'  is  almost  a  term  of  abuse.  It  is 
applied,  however,  without  much  discrimination.  Thus  Lewis 
Morgan  is  called  an  evolutionist,  although  he  rejected  the  theory 
of  organic  evolution  and  in  relation  to  society  believed,  not  in 
evolution,  but  in  progress,  which  he  conceived  as  the  steady 
material  and  moral  improvement  of  mankind  from  crude  stone 
implements  and  sexual  promiscuity  to  the  steam  engines  and 
monogamous  marriage  of  Rochester,  N.Y.  But  even  such  anti- 
evolutionists  as  Boas  believe  in  progress. 

It  is  convenient,  I  think,  to  use  the  term  'progress'  for  the 
process  by  which  human  beings  attain  to  greater  control  over  the 
physical  environment  through  the  increase  of  knowledge  and 
improvement  of  technique  by  inventions  and  discoveries.  Th 
way  in  which  we  are  now  able  to  destroy  considerable  portions  o 
cities  from  the  air  is  one  of  the  latest  striking  results  of  progress 
Progress  is  not  the  same  thing  as  social  evolution,  but  it  is 
very  closely  connected  with  it. 

Evolution,  as  I  understand  the  term,  refers  specifically  to  a 
process  of  emergence  of  new  forms  of  structure.  Organic 
evolution  has  two  important  features:  (i)  in  the  course  of  it  a 
small  number  of  kinds  of  organisms  have  given  rise  to  a  very  much 
larger  number  of  kinds;  (2)  more  complex  forms  of  organic 
structure  have  come  into  existence  by  development  out  of  simpler 
forms.  While  I  am  unable  to  attach  any  definite  meaning  to  such 
phrases  as  the  evolution  of  culture  or  the  evolution  of  language, 
I  think  that  social  evolution  is  a  reality  which  the  social  anthropo- 
logist should  recognise  and  study.  Like  organic  evolution,  it  can 
be  defined  by  two  features.  There  has  been  a  process  by  which, 
from  a  small  number  of  forms  of  social  structure,  many  different 
forms  have  arisen  in  the  course  of  history;  that  is,  there  has  been  a 
process  of  diversification.  Secondly,  throughout  this  process  more 
complex  forms  of  social  structures  have  developed  out  of,  or 
replaced,  simpler  forms. 

Just  how  structural  systems  are  to  be  classified  with  reference 
to  their  greater  or  less  complexity  is  a  problem  requiring  in- 
vestigation. But  there  is  evidence  of  a  fairly  close  correlation 


204  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

between  complexity  and  anotlitr  feature  of  structural  systems, 
namely,  the  extent  of  the  field  of  social  relations.  In  a  structural 
system  with  a  narrow  total  social  field,  an  average  or  typical 
person  is  brought  into  direct  and  indirect  social  relations  with 
only  a  small  number  of  other  persons.  In  systems  of  this  type  we 
may  find  that  the  linguistic  community — the  body  of  persons 
who  speak  one  language — numbers  from  250  to  5C0,  while  the 
political  community  is  even  smaller,  and  economic  relations  by  the 
exchange  of  goods  and  services  extend  only  over  a  very  narrow 
range.  Apart  from  the  differentiation  by  sex  and  age,  there  is  very 
little  differentiation  of  social  role  between  persons  or  classes.  We 
can  contrast  with  this  the  systems  of  social  structure  that  we  observe 
today  in  England  or  the  United  States.  Thus  the  process  of  human 
history  to  which  I  think  the  term  social  evolution  may  be  ap- 
propriately applied  might  be  defined  as  the  process  by  which 
wide-range  systems  of  social  structure  have  grown  out  of,  or 
replaced,  narrow-range  systems.  Whether  this  view  is  acceptable 
or  not,  I  suggest  that  the  concept  of  social  evolution  is  one  which 
requires  to  be  defined  in  terms  of  social  structure. 

There  is  no  time  on  this  occasion  to  discuss  the  relation  of  the 
study  of  social  structure  to  the  study  of  culture.  For  an  interesting 
attempt  to  bring  the  two  kinds  of  study  together  I  would  refer 
you  to  Mr.  Gregory  Bateson's  book  N avert.  I  have  made  no  attempt 
to  deal  with  social  anthropology  as  a  whole  and  with  all  its  various 
branches  and  divisions.  I  have  endeavoured  only  to  give  you  a  very 
general  idea  of  the  kind  of  study  to  which  I  have  found  it  scienti- 
fically profitable  to  devote  a  considerable  and  steadily  increasing 
proportion  of  my  time  and  energy.  The  only  reward  that  I  have 
sought  I  think  I  have  in  some  measure  found — something  of  the 
kind  of  insight  into  the  nature  of  the  world  of  which  we  are  part 
that  only  the  patient  pursuit  of  the  method  of  natural  science  can 
afford. 


CHAPTER     XI 

SOCIAL   SANCTIONS! 

IN  any  community  there  are  certain  modes  of  behaviour  which 
are  usual  and  which  characterise  that  particular  community. 
Such  modes  of  behaviour  may  be  called  usages.  All  social 
usages  have  behind  them  the  authority  of  the  society,  but  among 
them  some  are  sanctioned  and  others  are  not.  A  sanction  is  a 
reaction  on  the  part  of  a  society  or  of  a  considerable  number  of  its 
members  to  a  mode  of  behaviour  which  is  thereby  approved 
(positive  sanctions)  or  disapproved  (negative  sanctions).  Sanctions 
may  further  be  distinguished  according  to  whether  they  are 
diffuse  or  organised;  the  former  are  spontaneous  expressions  of 
approval  or  disapproval  by  members  of  the  community  acting 
as  individuals,  while  the  latter  are  social  actions  carried  out 
according  to  some  traditional  and  recognised  procedure.  It  is  a 
significant  fact  that  in  all  human  societies  the  negative  sanctions 
are  more  definite  than  the  positive.  Social  obligations  may  be 
defined  as  rules  of  behaviour  the  failure  to  observe  which  entails 
a  negative  sanction  of  some  sort.  These  are  thus  distinguished 
from  non-obligatory  social  usages,  as,  for  example,  customary 
technical  procedures. 

The  sanctions  existing  in  a  community  constitute  motives  in 
the  individual  for  the  regulation  of  his  conduct  in  conformity  with 
usage.  They  are  effective,  first,  through  the  desire  of  the  individual 
to  obtain  the  approbation  and  to  avoid  the  disapprobation  of  his 
fellows,  to  win  such  rewards  or  to  avoid  such  punishment  as  the 
community  offers  or  threatens;  and,  second,  through  the  fact 
that  the  individual  learns  to  react  to  particular  modes  of  behaviour 
with  judgments  of  approval  and  disapproval  in  the  same  way  as  do 
his  fellows,  and  therefore  measures  his  own  behaviour  both  in 
anticipation  and  in  retrospect  by  standards  which  conform  more 
or  less  closely  to  those  prevalent  in  the  community  to  which  he 
belongs.  What  is  called  conscience  is  thus  in  the  widest  sense  the 
reflex  in  the  individual  of  the  sanctions  of  the  society. 

^  Reprinted  from  the  Encyclopeedia  of  the  Social  Sciences,  Macmillan  Co. , 
New  York,  1933,  Vol.  XIII,  pp.  531-4. 

205 


206  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION    IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

It  is  convenient  to  begin  a  discussion  of  sanctions  by  a 
consideration  of  the  diffuse  negative  sanctions,  comprising 
reactions  tovi^ard  the  particular  or  general  behaviour  of  a  member 
of  the  community  which  constitute  judgments  of  disapproval. 
In  such  reactions  there  are  not  only  differences  of  degree — for 
disapproval  is  felt  and  expressed  with  different  degrees  of  in- 
tensity— but  also  differences  of  kind.  Such  differences  are  difficult 
to  define  and  classify.  In  the  English  language,  for  example, 
there  are  a  large  number  of  words  which  express  disapproval  of 
individual  behaviour;  these  vary  from  discourteous,  unmannerly, 
unseemly  and  unworthy,  through  improper,  discreditable, 
dishonourable  and  disreputable,  to  outrageous  and  infamous. 
Every  society  or  culture  has  its  own  ways  of  judging  behaviour, 
and  these  might  conveniently  be  studied  in  the  first  instance 
through  the  vocabulary.  But  until  comparative  study  of  societies 
of  different  types  has  proceeded  further  no  systematic  classification 
of  the  kinds  of  diffuse  negative  sanction  is  possible.  Provisionally 
the  negative  moral  or  ethical  sanction  may  be  defined  as  a  reaction 
of  reprobation  by  the  community  toward  a  person  whose  conduct 
is  disapproved;  moral  obligations  may  thus  be  considered  as 
rules  of  conduct  which,  if  not  observed,  bring  about  a  reaction 
of  this  kind.  Another  distinguishable  sanction  is  that  whereby 
the  behaviour  of  an  individual  is  met  with  ridicule  on  the 
part  of  his  fellows;  this  has  been  called  the  satirical  sanction. 
The  varieties  of  diffuse  positive  sanctions,  being  less  definite 
than  negative  sanctions,  are  therefore  still  more  difficult  to 
classify. 

From  the  diffuse  sanctions  already  described  there  should  be 
distinguished  what  may  be  called  (by  a  wide  extension  of  the 
term)  religious  sanctions;  these  have  also  been  named  supernatural 
sanctions  and  mystic  sanctions,  but  both  these  terms  have 
unsatisfactory  connotations.  The  religious  sanctions  are  constituted 
in  any  community  by  the  existence  of  certain  beliefs  which  are 
themselves  obligatory;  it  is  therefore  only  within  a  religious 
community  that  these  sanctions  exist.  They  take  the  form  that 
certain  deeds  by  an  individual  produce  a  modification  in  his 
religious  condition,  in  either  a  desirable  (good)  or  an  undesirable 
(evil)  direction.  Certain  acts  are  regarded  as  pleasing  to  gods  or 
spirits  or  as  establishing  desirable  relations  with  them,  while 
others  displease   them  or  destroy  in  some  way  the   desirable 


SOCIAL   SANCTIONS  207 

harmonious  relations.  The  reUgious  condition  of  the  individual 
is  in  these  instances  conceived  to  be  determined  by  his  relation 
to  personal  spiritual  beings.  The  change  in  the  religious  condition 
may  elsewhere  be  regarded  as  the  immediate  effect  of  the  act  itself, 
not  mediated  by  its  effects  on  some  personal  god  or  spirit,  a  view 
common  not  only  in  many  of  the  simpler  societies,  but  also  found 
in  a  special  form  in  Buddhism  and  in  other  advanced  Indian 
religions.  Sin  may  be  defined  as  any  mode  of  behaviour  which  falls 
under  a  negative  religious  sanction;  there  is  no  convenient  term 
for  the  opposite  of  sin,  that  is  an  action  which  produces  religious 
merit  or  a  desirable  ritual  condition. 

The  religious  sanctions  involve  the  belief  that  most  un- 
satisfactory ritual  or  religious  conditions  (pollution,  uncleanness, 
sinfulness)  can  be  removed  or  neutralised  by  socially  prescribed 
or  recognised  procedures,  such  as  lustration,  sacrifice,  penance, 
confession  and  repentance.  These  expiatory  rites  are  also  con- 
sidered to  act  either  immediately,  or  mediately  through  their 
effects  on  gods  or  spirits,  depending  upon  whether  the  sin  is 
regarded  as  acting  in  the  one  way  or  the  other. 

While  in  modem  western  civilisation  a  sin  is  usually  regarded 
as  necessarily  a  voluntary  action  or  thought,  in  many  simple 
societies  an  involuntary  action  may  fall  within  the  given  definition 
of  sin.  Sickness — for  example,  leprosy  among  the  Hebrews — is 
often  regarded  as  similar  to  ritual  or  religious  pollution  and  as 
therefore  requiring  expiation  or  ritual  purification.  A  condition  of 
ritual  or  rehgious  impurity  is  normally  considered  as  one  of  im- 
mediate or  ultimate  danger  to  the  individual;  it  may  be  believed 
that  he  will  fall  sick  and  perhaps  die  unless  he  can  be  purified. 
In  some  religions  the  religious  sanction  takes  the  form  of  a  belief 
that  an  individual  who  sins  in  this  life  will  suffer  some  form  of 
retribution  in  an  after-life.  In  many  instances  an  individual 
who  is  ritually  unclean  is  looked  upon  as  a  source  of  danger  not 
only  to  himself  but  also  to  those  with  whom  he  comes  in  contact 
or  to  the  whole  community.  He  may  therefore  be  more  or  less 
excluded  for  a  time  or  even  permanently  from  participation  in  the 
social  life  of  the  community.  Frequently,  if  not  always,  an 
obligation  therefore  rests  upon  the  sinner,  or  unclean  person, 
to  undertake  the  necessary  process  of  purification. 

Thus  the  religious  sanctions  differ  from  the  other  diffuse 
sanctions  by  reason  of  the  beliefs  and  conceptions  indicated  above, 


2o8  STRUCTURE  AND  FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

which  cannot  be  defined  or  described  in  any  simple  way.  Somewhat 
similar  beliefs  underlie  magical  practices  and  procedure  in  relation 
to  luck,  but  whereas  religious  observances  and  the  beliefs  associated 
with  them  are  obligatory  within  a  given  religious  community, 
the  former  are  comparable  with  technical  procedures,  customary 
but  not  obligatory. 

Organised  sanctions  are  to  be  regarded  as  special  developments 
of  the  diffuse  sanctions,  frequently  under  the  influence  of  the 
beliefs  belonging  to  religion.  Organised  positive  sanctions,  or 
premial  sanctions,  are  rarely  developed  to  any  great  extent. 
Honours,  decorations,  titles  and  other  rewards  for  merit,  including 
monetary  rewards  such  as  special  pensions,  given  to  individuals 
by  a  community  as  a  whole,  are  characteristic  of  modem  societies. 
In  preliterate  societies  a  man  who  has  slain  an  enemy  may  be 
given  the  right  to  distinguish  himself  by  wearing  some  special 
decoration  or  in  other  ways. 

Organised  negative  sanctions,  important  among  which  are  the 
penal  sanctions  of  criminal  law,  are  definite  recognised  procedures 
directed  against  persons  whose  behaviour  is  subject  to  social 
disapproval.  There  are  many  varieties  of  such  procedures,  the  most 
important  and  widespread  being  the  following:  subjection  to 
open  expression  of  reprobation  or  derision,  as,  for  example, 
through  forcible  public  exposure  by  confinement  in  stocks; 
partial  exclusion,  permanent  or  temporary,  from  full  participation 
in  social  life  and  its  privileges,  including  permanent  or  temporary 
loss  of  civil  or  religious  rights;  specific  loss  of  social  rank,  or 
degradation,  the  exact  contrary  of  the  positive  sanction  of  pro- 
motion; infliction  of  loss  of  property  by  imposition  of  a  fine  or  by 
forcible  seizure  or  destruction;  infliction  of  bodily  pain;  mutilation 
or  branding  in  which  pain  is  incidental  to  permanent  exposure  to 
reprobation;  permanent  exclusion  from  the  community,  as  by 
exile;  imprisonment;  and  punishment  by  death.  These  sanctions 
are  legal  sanctions  when  they  are  imposed  by  a  constituted 
authority,  political,  military  or  ecclesiastic. 

In  any  given  society  the  various  primary  sanctions  form  a  more 
or  less  systematic  whole  which  constitutes  the  machinery  of 
social  control.  There  is  an  intimate  relation  between  the  religious 
sanctions  and  the  moral  sanctions,  which  varies,  however,  in 
diff"erent  societies,  and  cannot  be  stated  in  any  brief  formula. 
The  primary  legal  sanctions  of  criminal  law,   in  all  societies 


SOCIAL  SANCTIONS  20  9 

except  the  highly  secularised  modern  states,  show  a  close  con- 
nection with  religious  beliefs. 

Besides  these  primary  social  sanctions  and  resting  upon  them 
there  are  certain  sanctions  which  may  be  termed  secondary; 
these  are  concerned  with  the  actions  of  persons  or  groups  in  their 
effects  upon  other  persons  or  groups.  In  modern  civil  law,  for 
example,  when  an  individual  is  ordered  by  a  court  to  pay  damages, 
the  primary  sanction  behind  the  order  is  the  power  of  the  court 
to  make  forcible  seizure  of  his  property  or  to  imprison  or  otherwise 
punish  him  for  contempt  of  court  if  he  fails  to  obey.  Thus 
secondary  sanctions  consist  of  procedures  carried  out  by  a 
community,  generally  through  its  representatives,  or  by  individuals 
with  the  approval  of  the  community,  when  recognised  rights 
have  been  infringed.  They  are  based  upon  the  general  principle 
that  any  person  who  has  suffered  injury  is  entitled  to  satisfaction 
and  that  such  satisfaction  should  be  in  some  way  proportioned  to 
the  extent  of  the  injury. 

One  class  of  such  procedures  consists  of  acts  of  retaliation,  by 
which  is  meant  socially  approved,  controlled  and  limited  acts  of 
revenge.  Thus  in  an  Australian  tribe  when  one  man  has  committed 
an  offence  against  another,  the  latter  is  permitted  by  public 
opinion,  often  definitely  expressed  by  the  older  men,  to  throw  a 
certain  number  of  spears  or  boomerangs  at  the  former  or  in  some 
instances  to  spear  him  in  the  thigh.  After  he  has  been  given  such 
satisfaction  he  may  no  longer  harbour  ill  feelings  against  the 
offender.  In  many  preliterate  societies  the  killing  of  an  individual 
entitles  the  group  to  which  he  belongs  to  obtain  satisfaction  by 
killing  the  offender  or  some  member  of  his  group.  In  regulated 
vengeance  the  offending  group  must  submit  to  this  as  an  act  of 
justice  and  must  not  attempt  further  retaliation.  Those  who  have 
received  such  satisfaction  are  felt  to  have  no  further  grounds  for 
ill  feeling. 

Satisfaction  for  injury  may  be  obtained  also  through  the  duel,  a 
recognised  and  controlled  combat  between  individuals,  or  through 
similar  combats  between  two  groups.  Among  Australian  tribes 
duelling  with  spears,  boomerangs,  clubs  and  shields  or  stone 
knives,  with  the  bystanders  ready  to  interfere  if  they  think  things 
are  going  too  far,  is  a  frequently  adopted  alternative  to  one-sided 
retaliation.  In  these  same  tribes  there  are  similar  regulated 
combats  between  two  groups,  sometimes  in  the  presence  of  other 


2IO  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

groups  who  see  that  there  is  fair  play.  It  is  often  difficult  to  draw  a 
dividing  line  between  such  group  combats  and  warfare;  in  fact 
they  may  possibly  be  regarded  as  a  special  kind  of  warfare 
characteristic  of  primitive  rather  than  of  civilised  societies. 
Frequently,  therefore,  war  may  be  regarded  as  a  secondary 
social  sanction  similar  to  the  duel.  A  political  group  maintains 
recognition  of  its  rights  by  the  threat  of  war  if  those  rights  should 
be  infringed.  Even  in  the  simplest  societies  it  is  recognised  that 
certain  acts  are  right  in  war  and  others  are  wrong  and  that  a 
declaration  of  war  may  be  just  in  certain  circumstances  and  in 
others  unjust,  so  that  the  conduct  of  warfare  is  to  some  extent 
controlled  by  diffuse  sanctions. 

Indemnification  is  often  found  as  an  alternative  to  retaliation  as 
a  means  of  giving  and  receiving  satisfaction.  An  indemnity  is 
something  of  value  given  by  a  person  or  group  to  another  person  or 
group  in  order  to  remove  or  neutralise  the  effects  of  an  infringe- 
ment of  rights.  It  may  be  distinguished  from  a  propitiatory  gift 
by  the  fact  that  it  is  obligatory  (i.e.  subject  to  a  negative  sanction, 
diffuse  or  organised)  in  the  particular  circumstances.  A  payment 
made  in  anticipation  of  an  invasion  of  rights  with  the  consent 
of  the  person  or  persons  receiving  it  may  be  regarded  as  an  in- 
demnity. Thus  in  many  societies  taking  a  woman  in  marriage 
is  regarded  as  an  invasion  of  the  rights  of  her  family  and  kin, 
so  that  before  they  consent  to  part  with  her  they  must  receive 
an  indemnity  or  the  promise  of  such.  In  these  cases  the  process  of 
indemnification  bears  some  similarity  to  that  of  purchase,  which  is 
a  transfer  of  rights  of  property  for  a  consideration. 

In  many  preliterate  societies  procedures  of  indemnification 
are  carried  out  under  the  diffuse  sanction  of  public  opinion, 
which  compels  an  individual  to  indemnify  one  whose  rights  he  has 
infringed.  In  some  societies  there  is  a  recognised  right  of  an  injured 
person  to  indemnify  himself  by  forcible  seizure  of  the  property  of 
the  offender.  When  society  becomes  politically  organised,  pro- 
cedures of  retaliation  and  indemnification,  backed  by  diffuse 
sanctions,  give  place  to  legal  sanctions  backed  by  the  power  of 
judicial  authorities  to  inflict  punishment.  Thus  arises  civil  law, 
by  which  a  person  who  has  suffered  an  infringement  of  rights 
may  obtain  reparation  or  restitution  from  the  person  responsible. 

In  a  consideration  of  the  functions  of  social  sanctions  it  is  not 
the  effects  of  the  sanction  upon  the  person  to  whom  they  are 


SOCIAL  SANCTIONS  211 

applied  that  are  most  important  but  rather  the  general  effects 
within  the  community  applying  the  sanctions.  For  the  application 
of  any  sanction  is  a  direct  affirmation  of  social  sentiments  by 
the  community  and  thereby  constitutes  an  important,  possibly 
essential,  mechanism  for  maintaining  these  sentiments.  Organised 
negative  sanctions  in  particular,  and  to  a  great  extent  the  secondary 
sanctions,  are  expressions  of  a  condition  of  social  dysphoria 
brought  about  by  some  deed.  The  function  of  the  sanction  is  to 
restore  the  social  euphoria  by  giving  definite  collective  expression 
to  the  sentiments  which  have  been  affected  by  the  deed,  as  in  the 
primary  sanctions  and  to  some  extent  in  the  secondary  sanctions, 
or  by  removing  a  conflict  within  the  community  itself.  The  sanc- 
tions are  thus  of  primary  significance  to  sociology  in  that  they 
are  reactions  on  the  part  of  a  community  to  events  affecting  its 
integration. 


CHAPTER    XII 

PRIMITIVE   LAWi 

MANY  historical  jurists  in  contrast  with  the  analytical  school 
have  used  the  term  law  to  include  most  if  not  all  processes 
of  social  control.  The  term  is,  however,  usually  confined 
to  'social  control  through  the  systematic  application  of  the  force 
of  politically  organised  society'  (Pound).  The  limited  application, 
more  convenient  for  purposes  of  sociological  analysis  and  classi- 
fication, will  be  adopted  in  this  article;  the  field  of  law  will  there- 
fore be  regarded  as  coterminous  with  that  of  organised  legal 
sanctions.  The  obligations  imposed  on  individuals  in  societies 
where  there  are  no  legal  sanctions  will  be  regarded  as  matters  of 
custom  and  convention  but  not  of  law;  in  this  sense  some  simple 
societies  have  no  law,  although  all  have  customs  which  are  sup- 
ported by  sanctions. 

The  confusion  which  has  resulted  in  the  attempt  to  apply  to 
preliterate  societies  the  modern  distinction  between  criminal  law 
and  civil  law  can  be  avoided  by  making  instead  the  distinction 
between  the  law  of  public  delicts  and  the  law  of  private  delicts. 
In  any  society  a  deed  is  a  public  delict  if  its  occurrence  normally 
leads  to  an  organised  and  regular  procedure  by  the  whole  com- 
munity or  by  the  constituted  representatives  of  social  authority, 
which  results  in  the  fixing  of  responsibility  upon  some  person 
within  the  community  and  the  infliction  by  the  community  or  by 
its  representatives  of  some  hurt  or  punishment  upon  the  respon- 
sible person.  This  procedure,  which  may  be  called  the  penal 
sanction,  is  in  its  basic  form  a  reaction  by  the  community  against 
an  action  of  one  of  its  own  members  which  off'ends  some  strong 
and  definite  moral  sentiment  and  thus  produces  a  condition  of 
social  dysphoria.  The  immediate  function  of  the  reaction  is  to 
give  expression  to  a  collective  feeling  of  moral  indignation  and  so 
to  restore  the  social  euphoria.  Its  ultimate  function  is  to  maintain 
the  moral  sentiment  in  question  at  the  requisite  degree  of  strength 
in  the  individuals  who  constitute  the  community. 

^  Reprinted  from  the  Encyclopcedia  of  the  Social  Sciences,  Macmillan  Co., 
New  York,  1933,  Vol.  IX,  pp.  202-6. 

212 


PRIMITIVE  LAW  213 

Comparatively  little  precise  information  is  available  concerning 
penal  sanctions  in  preliterate  societies.  Among  the  actions  which 
are  known  to  be  treated  as  public  delicts  in  the  simpler  societies 
are  incest,  i.e.  marriage  or  sexual  congress  with  persons  with  whom 
such  relations  are  forbidden;  sorcery,  or  evil  magic,  by  one  person 
against  another  within  the  community;  repeated  breaches  of 
tribal  custom;  and  various  forms  of  sacrilege.  In  many  preliterate 
societies  the  penal  sanction  is  applied  principally  if  not  solely  to 
actions  which  infringe  upon  customs  regarded  by  the  community 
as  sacred,  so  that  the  sanction  itself  may  almost  be  regarded  as  a 
special  form  of  ritual  sanction.  Ritual  sanctions  are  derived  from 
the  belief  that  certain  actions  or  events  render  an  individual  or  a 
group  ritually  unclean,  or  polluted,  so  that  some  specific  action 
is  required  to  remove  the  pollution.  In  many  examples  of  penal 
sanction  it  may  plausibly  be  held  that  a  deed  such  as  incest 
produces  a  pollution  of  the  whole  community  within  which  it 
occurs  and  that  the  punishment,  which  may  mean  the  killing  of  the 
guilty  persons,  is  a  means  of  cleansing  the  community.  Upon  the 
establishment  of  a  political  or  executive  authority  even  of  the 
simplest  kind  disobedience  of  that  authority's  commands  may  be 
subject  to  penal  sanctions  and  treated  as  a  public  delict;  moreover, 
direct  offences  against  the  constituted  authority  or  against  the 
persons  in  whom  that  authority  rests  may  be  subject  to  penal 
sanctions.  Thus  when  the  social  authority  rests  in  chiefs,  an 
offence  which  would  be  a  private  delict  if  committed  against  a 
commoner  may  be  treated  as  a  public  delict  when  committed 
against  a  chief. 

In  the  procedure  of  a  law  of  private  delicts  a  person  or  a  body 
of  persons  that  has  suffered  some  injury,  loss  or  damage  by  in- 
fringement of  recognised  rights  appeals  to  a  constituted  judicial 
authority,  who  declares  some  other  person  or  body  of  persons 
within  the  community  to  be  responsible  and  rules  that  the  de- 
fendant shall  give  satisfaction  to  the  plaintiff,  such  satisfaction 
frequently  taking  the  form  of  the  payment  of  an  indemnity  or 
damages.  A  private  delict  is  thus  ai  action  which  is  subject  to 
what  may  be  called  a  restitutive  sanction.  The  law  of  private 
delicts  in  preliterate  societies  corresponds  to  the  civil  law  of 
modern  times.  There  are,  however,  certain  important  differences. 
In  general  in  modern  law  actions  which  fall  simply  under  civil  law 
are  those  which  cause  damage  but  are  not  subject  to  reprobation. 


214  STRUCTURE   AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE  SOCIETY 

Consequently,  although  the  civil  sanction  expressed  through 
the  payment  of  damages  causes  loss  to  the  defendant,  it  is  not 
specifically  punitive.  Even  in  modern  civil  law,  however,  a 
magistrate  may  in  special  instances  award  'punitive  damages', 
thereby  expressing  the  view  that  the  injury  committed  is  of  such 
a  kind  as  to  be  properly  subject  to  reprobation  and  therefore  to 
punishment.  In  modern  law  when  a  deed  is  an  offence  against 
morality  and  at  the  same  time  inflicts  injury  it  may  become 
actionable  under  both  criminal  and  civil  law.  The  emphasis  in  the 
punishment  for  homicide  or  theft  is  on  its  aspect  as  an  offence 
against  the  community  rather  than  on  the  principle  that  resti- 
tution should  be  made  to  those  who  have  suffered  by  the  deed. 

In  preliterate  societies  private  delicts  are  for  the  most  part 
killing,  wounding,  theft,  adultery  and  failure  to  pay  debts;  and 
while  they  are  primarily  regarded  as  constituting  an  injury  to 
some  member  of  the  community  they  are  subject  also  to  moral 
reprobation  as  anti-social  actions.  The  sanction  is  frequently  both 
restitutive  and  repressive,  giving  satisfaction  to  the  injured  person 
and  inflicting  punishment  upon  the  person  responsible  for  the 
injury;  for  example,  in  some  African  tribes  a  thief  is  required 
to  restore  to  the  person  whom  he  has  robbed  double  the  value 
of  what  he  has  taken.  In  its  basic  form  the  law  of  private  delicts 
is  a  procedure  for  avoiding  or  relieving  the  social  dysphoria  which 
results  from  conflicts  within  a  community.  An  offence  committed 
against  another  member  or  group  of  the  same  community,  by 
inflicting  a  sense  of  injury  upon  the  victim,  creates  a  disturbance 
of  the  social  life  which  ceases  only  when  satisfaction  is  rendered 
to  the  injured  person  or  persons.  Thus  in  African  native  law  a 
judge  is  not  regarded  as  having  properly  settled  a  case  until  all 
parties  concerned  are  satisfied  with  the  settlement. 

The  distinction  between  public  delicts  and  private  delicts 
illustrates  the  fact  that  the  law  has  no  single  origin.  A  deed 
committed  by  a  member  of  the  community  which  offends  the 
moral  sense  of  the  community  may  be  subject  to  three  sanctions, 
the  general  or  diffuse  moral  sanction,  which  makes  the  guilty 
person  subject  to  the  reprobation  of  his  fellows;  the  ritual  sanction, 
which  produces  in  the  guilty  person  a  condition  of  ritual  un- 
cleanness  that  constitutes  a  danger  to  himself  and  to  those  with 
whom  he  is  in  contact — in  such  cases  custom  may  require  him  to 
undergo  ritual  purification  or  expiation  or  it  may  be  believed  that 


PRIMITIVE   LAW  215 

as  a  result  of  his  sin  he  will  fall  ill  and  die;  the  penal  sanction, 
whereby  the  community  through  certain  persons  acting  as  its 
constituted  judicial  authorities  inflicts  punishment  on  the  guilty 
person,  which  may  be  regarded  either  as  a  collective  expression 
of  the  moral  indignation  aroused  by  the  deed  or  as  a  means  of 
removing  the  ritual  pollution  resulting  from  the  deed  by  imposing 
an  expiation  upon  the  guilty  person,  or  as  both. 

On  the  other  hand,  an  action  which  constitutes  an  infringe- 
ment of  the  rights  of  a  person  or  group  of  persons  may  lead  to 
retaliation  on  the  part  of  the  injured  against  the  person  or  group 
responsible  for  the  injury.  When  such  acts  of  retaliation  are 
recognised  by  custom  as  justifiable  and  are  subject  to  a  customary 
regulation  of  procedure,  various  forms  of  retaliatory  sanctions 
-^  may  be  said  to  prevail.  In  preliterate  society  generally  warfare 
has  such  a  sanction;  the  waging  of  war  is  in  some  communities, 
as  among  the  Australian  hordes,  normally  an  act  of  retaliation 
carried  out  by  one  group  against  another  that  is  held  responsible 
for  an  injury  suffered,  and  the  procedure  is  regulated  by  a 
recognised  body  of  customs  which  is  equivalent  to  the  international 
law  of  modern  nations.  The  institution  of  organised  and  regulated 
vengeance  is  another  example  of  a  retaliatory  sanction.  The 
killing  of  a  man,  whether  intentional  or  accidental,  constitutes  an 
injury  to  his  clan,  local  community  or  kindred,  for  which  satis- 
faction is  required.  The  injured  group  is  regarded  as  justified 
in  seeking  vengeance  and  there  is  frequently  an  obligation  on  the 
members  of  the  group  to  avenge  the  death.  The  retaliator}^  action 
is  regulated  by  custom;  the  lex  talionis  requires  that  the  damage 
inflicted  shall  be  equivalent  to  the  damage  suffered  and  the  prin- 
ciple of  collective  solidarity  permits  the  avengers  to  kill  a  person 
other  than  the  actual  murderer,  for  example  his  brother,  or  in  some 
instances  any  member  of  his  clan.  When  the  institution  is  com- 
pletely organised,  custom  requires  the  group  responsible  for  the 
first  death  to  accept  the  killing  of  one  of  their  number  as  an  act 
of  justice  and  to  make  no  further  retaliation.  Retaliatory  sanctions 
may  also  appear  in  relation  to  injuries  of  one  person  by  another; 
for  example,  the  recognised  right  in  certain  circumstances  of  one 
person  to  challenge  another  to  fight  a  duel.  Among  Australian 
tribes  an  individual  who  has  suffered  injury  from  another  may 
by  agreement  of  the  elders  be  given  the  right  to  obtain  satis- 
faction by  throwing  spears  or  boomerangs  at  him  or  by  spearing 


2l6  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

him  in  a  non- vital  part  of  the  body,  such  as  the  thigh.  In  all 
instances  of  retaliatory  sanction  there  is  a  customary  procedure 
for  satisfying  the  injured  person  or  group  whereby  resentment 
may  be  expressed,  frequently  by  inflicting  hurt  upon  the  person 
or  group  responsible  for  the  injury.  Where  it  works  effectively 
the  result  is  to  provide  an  expiation  for  the  offence  and  to  remove 
the  feeling  of  injury  or  resentment  in  the  injured  person  or  persons. 
In  many  societies  retaliation  is  replaced  more  or  less  by  a  system 
of  indemnities;  persons  or  groups  having  injured  other  persons  or 
groups  provide  satisfaction  to  the  latter  by  handing  over  certain 
valuables.  The  procedure  of  providing  satisfaction  by  indemnity 
is  widespread  in  preliterate  societies  which  have  not  yet  developed 
a  legal  system  in  the  narrow  sense. 

Among  the  Yurok,  who  are  food  gatherers  and  hunters  living 
in  northern  California  in  small  villages  with  no  political  organisa- 
tion, there  is  no  regular  procedure  for  dealing  with  offences 
against  the  community  and  therefore  no  law  of  public  delicts. 
Injuries  and  offences  of  one  person  against  another  are  subject  to 
indemnities  regulated  by  custom;  every  invasion  of  privilege  or 
property  must  be  exactly  compensated;  for  the  killing  of  an  in- 
dividual an  indemnity  or  blood  money  must  be  paid  to  the  near 
kin.  After  a  feud  or  war  each  side  must  pay  for  those  who  have 
been  killed  on  the  other  side.  Only  the  fact  and  amount  of  damage 
are  considered;  never  the  question  of  intent,  malice,  negligence 
or  accident.  Once  an  indemnity  for  an  injury  has  been  accepted 
it  is  improper  for  the  injured  person  to  harbour  any  further 
resentment.  As  the  payment  of  indemnities  is  arranged  by 
negotiation  between  the  persons  concerned  and  not  by  appeal  to 
any  judicial  authority,  the  law  of  private  delicts  in  the  strict 
sense  is  not  present.  Among  the  Ifugao,  who  cultivate  rice  on 
terraced  hillsides  of  northern  Luzon  in  the  Philippines  and  who 
have  no  political  organisation  and  no  system  of  clans,  'society  does 
not  punish  injuries  to  itself  except  as  the  censure  of  public 
opinion  is  a  punishment';  that  is,  there  is  no  law  of  public  delicts, 
no  actual  penal  sanction.  Nevertheless,  a  person  who  practises 
sorcery  against  one  of  his  own  kin  is  put  to  death  by  his  kin; 
on  the  other  hand,  incest  between  brother  and  sister,  parricide 
and  fratricide  are  said  to  go  unpunished.  It  is  probable,  however, 
that  there  are  powerful  and  effective  ritual  sanctions  against  these 
acts.  An  offence  committed  by  one  person  against  another  person 


PRIMITIVE   LAW  217 

or  an  infringement  of  the  rights  of  one  person  by  another  is  the 
occasion  of  a  conflict  between  the  kindred  of  the  two  parties, 
including  relatives  through  btoh  father  and  mother  to  the  third 
or  fourth  degree.  Retaliation  by  the  killing  of  the  offender  or 
sometimes  of  one  of  his  kin  is  the  regular  method  of  obtaining 
satisfaction  in  cases  of  murder,  sorcery,  adultery  discovered  in 
flagrante,  refusal  to  pay  an  indemnity  assessed  for  injury  suffered, 
and  persistent  and  wilful  refusal  to  pay  a  debt  when  there  is  ability 
to  pay.  Satisfaction  is  provided  in  other  cases  by  the  payment  of 
indemnities.  There  are  no  judicial  authorities  before  whom 
disputes  may  be  brought;  the  negotiations  are  carried  out  by  a 
go-between  who  belongs  to  neither  of  the  two  opposed  groups  of 
kindred.  Certain  persons  obtain  renown  for  themselves  as  success- 
ful go-betweens,  but  such  persons  have  no  authority  and  are  not 
in  any  sense  representatives  of  the  community  as  a  whole.  During 
the  controversy  the  two  parties  are  in  a  condition  of  ritual  enmity 
or  opposition  and  when  a  settlement  is  reached  they  join  in  a 
peacemaking  ceremony.  A  scale  of  settlement  is  recognised  by 
custom  and  in  certain  circumstances  the  payments  vary  according 
to  the  class — ^wealthy,  middle  class  or  poor — to  which  the  group 
receiving  or  making  payment  belongs.  The  Ifugao  thus  have  an 
organised  system  of  justice,  which,  however,  does  not  constitute 
a  system  of  law  in  the  narrow  sense  of  the  term  since  there  is  no 
judicial  authority. 

An  important  step  is  taken  towards  the  formation  of  a  legal 
system  where  there  are  recognised  arbitrators  or  judges  who  hear 
evidence,  decide  upon  responsibility  and  assess  damages;  only 
the  existence  of  some  authority  with  power  to  enforce  the  judg- 
ments delivered  by  the  judges  is  then  lacking.  It  has  been  argued 
plausibly  that  in  some  societies  a  legal  system  for  dealing  with 
private  delicts  has  grown  up  in  this  manner;  disputes  are  brought 
before  arbitrators  who  declare  the  custom  and  apply  it  to  the 
case  before  them;  such  courts  of  arbitration  become  established 
as  regular  tribunals;  and  finally  there  is  developed  in  the  society 
some  procedure  for  enforcing  judgments. 

A  development  similar  to  this  is  illustrated  by  the  practices 
of  the  A-Kamba,  A-Kiku}T.i  and  A-Theraka,  Bantu  peoples  to  the 
south  and  south-east  of  Mount  Kenya  in  East  Africa  who  live 
in  scattered  household  communities,  keep  cattle,  sheep  and  goats 
and  grow  grain  in  hand-tilled  fields.  They  have  no  chiefs  and  are 


2l8  STRUCTURE  AND   FUNCTION   IN   PRIMITIVE   SOCIETY 

divided  into  well-defined  age  grades,  one  of  which  consists  of 
elders  who  exercise  both  priestly  and  judicial  functions.  If  there  is 
a  dispute  in  which  one  person  believes  his  rights  have  been  in- 
fringed by  another,  the  disputants  call  together  a  number  of  elders 
of  the  district  or  districts  in  which  they  live  and  these  constitute 
a  court  to  hear  the  case.  The  court  acts  primarily  as  a  court  of 
arbitration  and  as  a  means  of  deciding  upon  the  customary 
principles  of  justice  by  which  the  dispute  should  be  settled;  it 
usually  takes  no  steps  to  enforce  the  judgment  on  the  losing  party 
but  leaves  this  task  to  the  claimant.  In  serious  cases,  however, 
when  an  offence  affects  the  whole  community  or  when  the  accused 
is  regarded  as  an  habitual  and  dangerous  offender  so  that  public 
indignation  makes  the  affair  one  of  public  concern,  the  elders 
can  exercise  authority  to  enforce  judgment.  The  usual  procedure 
rests  on  the  ritual  powers  of  the  elders;  they  can  pronounce  a 
curse,  which  is  feared  as  inevitably  bringing  down  supernatural 
punishment,  on  a  person  who  refuses  to  obey  a  judgment.  The 
killing  of  a  member  of  one  clan  by  a  member  of  another,  whether 
intentional  or  accidental,  is  treated  by  the  court  of  elders  as  a 
private  delict  and  is  settled  by  the  payment  of  an  indemnity  to  the 
relatives  of  the  victim  by  the  killer  and  his  relatives.  The  elders 
also  possess  limited  powers  of  dealing  with  public  delicts  by  a 
procedure  known  as  kingolle,  or  mwinge.  If  a  person  is  held 
guilty  of  witchcraft  or  is  regarded  as  an  habitual  offender  and 
thus  as  a  public  danger,  the  elders  may  inflict  the  punishment  of 
death  or  may  destroy  the  offender's  homestead  and  expel  him  from 
the  district.  Before  such  action  may  be  taken  elders  from  remote 
regions  must  be  called  in  for  consultation  and  the  consent  of  near 
relatives  of  the  offender  must  be  obtained. 

The  Ashanti  afford  a  contrast  to  the  system  of  the  A-Kamba  in 
that  they  have  a  well  organised  law  of  public  delicts,  which  are 
designated  by  a  native  term  which  means  'things  hateful  to  the 
gods'.  These  include  murder,  suicide,  certain  sexual  offences 
including  incestuous  relations  with  certain  relatives  by  descent 
and  by  marriage,  certain  forms  of  abuse,  assault  and  stealing,  the 
invocation  of  a  curse  upon  a  chief,  treason,  cowardice,  witchcraft, 
the  violation  of  recognised  tribal  tabus  and  the  breaking  of  a  com- 
mand of  the  central  authority  issued  and  qualified  with  an  oath. 
The  Ashanti  conception  of  the  law  is  that  all  such  actions  are 
offences  against  the  sacred  or  supernatural  powers  on  which  the 


PRIMITIVE  LAW  219 

wellbeing  of  the  whole  community  depends  and  that  unless  these 
offences  are  expiated  by  the  punishment  of  the  guilty  persons  the 
whole  tribe  will  suffer.  The  judicial  functions  belong  to  the  king 
or  chief  (the  occupant  of  a  sacred  stool),  before  whom  the  offender 
is  tried.  The  punishment  for  the  more  serious  offences  is  de- 
capitation, although  in  certain  circumstances  the  condemned 
man  and  his  relatives  may  'buy  his  head';  that  is,  pay  a  redemp- 
tion price  by  which  his  life  may  be  saved.  The  courts  of  the  chiefs 
do  not  concern  themselves  with  private  delicts,  which  are  denoted 
'household  cases'  and  settled  by  the  authority  of  heads  of  kinship 
groups  or  by  negotiations.  A  dispute  concerning  a  private  delict 
may  be  brought  before  the  chief  indirectly  if  one  of  the  parties 
involved  swears  an  oath,  which  thus  makes  the  dispute  a  public 
matter. 

While  the  A-Kamba  elders  are  concerned  mainly  with  private 
delicts  and  the  Ashanti  chiefs  with  public  delicts,  there  are  tribes 
and  nations  in  Africa  and  elsewhere  in  which  the  central  authorities 
— the  chiefs  or  the  king  and  his  representatives — administer  both 
kinds  of  law,  which  may  always  be  differentiated  by  reference  to 
procedure.  In  the  law  of  private  delicts  a  dispute  between  persons 
or  groups  of  persons  is  brought  before  the  judicial  tribunal  for 
settlement;  in  the  law  of  public  delicts  the  central  authority  itself 
and  on  its  own  initiative  takes  action  against  an  offender.  Modern 
criminal  law  and  civil  law  are  directly  derived  respectively  from 
the  law  of  public  delicts  and  the  law  of  private  delicts;  but  acts 
which  are  now  regarded  as  characteristically  public  delicts,  such 
as  murder  and  theft,  are  in  many  preliterate  societies  treated  as 
private  delicts,  while  the  acts  which  in  such  societies  are  moot 
frequently  regarded  as  public  delicts  are  witchcraft,  incest  and 
sacrilege. 

In  its  most  elementary  developments  law  is  intimately  bound 
up  with  magic  and  religion;  legal  sanctions  are  closely  related  to 
ritual  sanctions,  A  full  understanding  of  the  beginnings  of  law 
in  simpler  societies  can  therefore  be  reached  only  by  a  comparative 
study  of  whole  systems  of  social  sanctions. 


TJ> 


UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA  LIBRARY 

Los  Angeles 
This  book  is  DUE  on  the  last  date  stamped  below. 


k^ 


4\MK  '       05  }W 


GN400R116S 


L  005  744  063  8 


GF 
ilO( 
Rll 


0't