Skip to main content

Full text of "The "Summa theologica" of St. Thomas Aquinas"

See other formats


'%', 


f¥ 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2011  with  funding  from 

University  of  Toronto 


http://www.archive.org/details/summatheologi08thom 


22>      ♦' 


THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA 


t» 


THE 

"SUMMA  THEOLOGICA 

'       OF 

ST.  THOMAS  AQUINAS 

PART  II. 

(FIRST  PART) 


>) 


LITERALLY    TRANSLATED    BY 


FATHERS  OF  THE  ENGLISH  DOMINICAN 

PROVINCE 


THIRD     NUMBER 
(QQ.   XC— CXIV.) 


R.  &  T.  WASHBOURNE,  LTD. 
PATERNOSTER   ROW,  LONDON 

AND  AT  MANCHESTER,  BIRMINGHAM,  AND  GLASGOW 
BENZIGER    BROTHERS  :    NEW    YORK,    CINCINNATI,    CHICAGO 

I9I5 
{All  rights  reserved] 


ihL  j.NoriTUTE  OF  MEDlAfV,' 

10  ELMSLEV   PLACt 
TOHOiMTO  6,    CANADA, 

OGT20  1S32 

Jlilul  (Dbstnt.  S  19  9 

F.  INNOCENTIUS  APAP.,  O.P.,  S.T.M., 

Censor  Theol. 

Jinprimatur. 

EDM.  CANONICUS  SURMONT, 

ViCARius  Generalis. 

Westmonasterii. 


APPROBATIO  ORDINIS. 

Ilihil  (Dbstnt. 

F.  H.  RAPHAEL  MOSS.  O.P.,  S.T.L. 
F.  V.  J.  McNABB,  O.P.,  S.T.B. 

imprimatur. 

F.  HUMBERTUS  EVEREST,  O.P.,  S.T.B. 

Prior  Provinxialis. 


LONDINI, 

Die  7  Martii,  1915. 


CONTENTS 


TREATISE  ON  LAW 

{a)  In  General 


ilUESTION 

XC.    OF  THE  ESSENCE  OF    LAW 

XCI.    OF  THE  VARIOUS  KINDS    OF    LAW 

XCII.    OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF    LAW 


(6)  In  Particular 


XCin.    OF    THE    ETERNAL    LAW  -  -  -  - 

XCIV.    OF    THE    NATURAL    LAW  .  -  -  - 

XCV.    OF    HUMAN    LAW  -  -  -  -  - 

XCVL    OF    THE    POWER    OF    HUMAN    LAW  -  .  . 

XCVir.    OF    CHANGE    IN    LAWS         .  -  -  .  - 

XCVIII.    OF    THE    OLD    LAW  -  .  .  -  * 

XCIX.    OF    THE    PRECEPTS    OF    THE    OLD    LAW        -  .  - 

C.    OF   THE    MORAL    PRECEPTS    OF    THE    OLD    LAW 
CI.    OF   THE    CEREMONIAL    PRECEPTS    IN    THEMSELVES 
CII.    OF   THE    CAUSES    OF    THE    CEREMONIAL    PRECEPTS 
CIII.    OF   THE    DURATION    OF   THE    CEREMONIAL    PRECEPTS 
CIV.    OF   THE    JUDICIAL   PRECEPTS  -  -  -  - 

CV.    OF    THE    REASON    FOR    THE    JUDICIAL    PRECEPTS 
CVI.    OF   THE   LAW    OF   THE   GOSPEL,     CALLED    THE    NEW    LAW, 
CONSIDERED    IN    ITSELF  -  -  .  - 

CVII.    OF    THE    NEW    LAW    AS    COMPARED    WITH    THE    OLD 
CVIII.    OF    THOSE    THINGS    THAT    ARE    CONTAINED     IN    THE    NEW 
LAW       ------- 


PAGE 
I 

9 

22 


27 

40 
53 

63 
76 
84 
99 

113 

148 

159 
225 

239 

248 

280 
291 

304 


TREATISE  ON  GRACE 

CIX.    OF   THE    NECESSITY    OF   GRACE 

ex.    OF   THE    GRACE    OF   GOD    AS    REGARDS  ITS    ESSENCE 

CXI.    OF    THE    DIVISION    OF   GRACE           -  -  - 

CXII.    OF    THE    CAUSE    OF   GRACE                 -  -  - 

CXIII.    OF   THE    EFFECTS    OF   GRACE           -  -  . 

CXIV.    OF    MERIT                   -                  _                  _  _  - 


323 
346 
356 
368 

379 
403 


TREATISE  ON  LAW 


THE   '^SUMMA   THEOLOGICA" 

FIRST  PART  OF  THE  SECOND  PART. 

QUESTION  XC. 

OF  THE  ESSENCE  OF  LAW. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  have  now  to  consider  the  extrinsic  principles  of  acts. 
Now  the  extrinsic  principle  inclining  to  evil  is  the  devil,  of 
whose  temptations  we  have  spoken  in  the  First  Part 
(Q.  CXI  v.).  But  the  extrinsic  principle  moving  to  good  is 
God,  Who  both  instructs  us  by  means  of  His  Law,  and 
assists  us  by  His  Grace :  wherefore  in  the  first  place  we  must 
speak  of  law;  in  the  second  place,  of  grace. 

Concerning  law,  we  must  consider — (i)  Law  itself  in 
general;  (2)  its  parts.  Concerning  law  in  general  three 
points  offer  themselves  for  our  consideration:  (i)  Its  essence; 
(2)  The  different  kinds  of  law ;  (3)  The  effects  of  law. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  law  is  something  pertaining  to  reason  ? 
(2)  Concerning  the  end  of  law.  (3)  Its  cause.  (4)  The  pro- 
mulgation of  law. 

First  Article, 
whether  law  is  something  pertaining  to  reason  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  law  is  not  something  pertaining 
to  reason.  For  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  vii.  23) :  /  see 
another  law  in  my  members,  etc.  But  nothing  pertaining  to 
reason  is  in  the  members;  since  the  reason  does  not  make 

n-  3  I 


Q.  90.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  2 

use  of  a  bodily  organ.     Therefore  law  is  not  something 
pertaining  to  reason. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  in  the  reason  there  is  nothing  else  but 
power,  habit,  and  act.  But  law  is  not  the  power  itself  of 
reason.  In  like  manner,  neither  is  it  a  habit  of  reason: 
because  the  habits  of  reason  are  the  intellectual  virtues  of 
which  we  have  spoken  above  (Q.  LVIL).  Nor  again  is  it 
an  act  of  reason:  because  then  law  would  cease,  when  the 
act  of  reason  ceases,  for  instance,  while  we  are  asleep. 
Therefore  law  is  nothing  pertaining  to  reason. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  law  moves  those  who  are  subject  to 
it  to  act  aright.  But  it  belongs  properly  to  the  will  to  move 
to  act,  as  is  evident  from  what  has  been  said  above  (Q.  IX., 
A.  i).  Therefore  law  pertains,  not  to  the  reason,  but  to 
the  will;  according  to  the  words  of  the  Jurist  (Lib.  i.  ff.,  De 
Const.  Prin.) :  Whatsoever  pleaseth  the  sovereign,  has  force  of 
law. 

On  the  contrary,  It  belongs  to  the  law  to  command  and  to 
forbid.  But  it  belongs  to  reason  to  command,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XVII.,  A.  f).  Therefore  law  is  something  per- 
taining to  reason. 

/  answer  that,  Law  is  a  rule  and  measure  of  acts,  whereby 
man  is  induced  to  act  or  is  restrained  from  acting:  for  lex 
(law)  is  derived  from  ligare  (to  bind),  because  it  binds  one 
to  act.  Now  the  rule  and  measure  of  human  acts  is  the 
reason,  which  is  the  first  principle  of  human  acts,  as  is  evident 
from  what  has  been  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  i  ad  3) ;  since  it 
belongs  to  the  reason  to  direct  to  the  end,  which  is  the  first 
principle  in  all  matters  of  action,  according  to  the  Philosopher 
(Phys.  ii.).  Now  that  which  is  the  principle  in  any  genus, 
is  the  rule  and  measure  of  that  genus:  for  instance,  unity  in 
the  gemls  of  numbers,  and  the  first  movement  in  the  genus 
of  movements.  Consequently  it  follows  that  law  is  some- 
thing pertaining  to  reason. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Since  law  is  a  kind  of  rule  and  measure,  it 
may  be  in  something  in  two  ways.  First,  as  in  that  which 
measures  and  rules:  and  since  this  is  proper  to  reason,  it 
follows  that,  in  this   way,  law  is  in  the  reason   alone. — 


3  THE  ESSENCE  OF  LAW         Q-  9o.  Art.  i 

Secondly,  as  in  that  which  is  measured  and  ruled.  In  this 
way,  law  is  in  all  those  things  that  are  inclined  to  something 
by  reason  of  some  law :  so  that  any  inclination  arising  from  a 
law,  may  be  called  a  law,  not  essentially  but  by  participation 
as  it  were.  And  thus  the  inchnation  of  the  members  to 
concupiscence  is  called  the  law  of  the  members. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Just  as,  in  external  action,  we  may  con- 
sider the  work  and  the  work  done,  for  instance  the  work  of 
building  and  the  house  built;  so  in  the  acts  of  reason,  we 
may  consider  the  act  itself  of  reason,  i.e.,  to  understand  and 
to  reason,  and  something  produced  by  this  act.  With 
regard  to  the  speculative  reason,  this  is  first  of  all  the 
definition;  secondly,  the  proposition;  thirdly,  the  syllogism 
or  argument.  And  since  also  the  practical  reason  makes 
use  of  a  syllogism  in  respect  of  the  work  to  be  done,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XIII.,  A.  3;  Q.  LXXVL,  A.  i)  and  as  the  Philoso- 
pher teaches  {Ethic,  vii.) ;  hence  we  find  in  the  practical 
reason  something  that  holds  the  same  position  in  regard 
to  operations,  as,  in  the  speculative  intellect,  the  proposition 
holds  in  regard  to  conclusions.  Suchlike  uniyer^sal^  propoj 
sitions  of  the  practical  intellect  that  are  directed  to  actions 
have  the  nature  of  law.  And  these  propositions  are  some- 
times under  our  actual  consideration,  while  sometimes  they 
are  retained  in  the  reason  by  means  of  a  habit. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Reason  has  its  power  of  moving  from  the 
will,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XVII.,  A.  i) :  for  it  is  due  to  the 
fact  that  one  wills  the  end,  that  the  reason  issues  its  com- 
mands as  regards  things  ordained  to  the  end.  But  in  order 
that  the  volition  of  what  is  commanded  may  have  the 
nature  of  law,  it  needs  to  be  in  accord  with  some  rule  of 
reason.  And  in  this  sense  is  to  be  imderstood  the  saying 
that  the  will  of  the  sovereign  has  the  force  of  law ;  otherwise 
the  sovereign's  will  would  savour  of  lawlessness  rather  than 
of  law. 


Q.  90.  A  RT.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  " 


Second  Article. 

whether  the  law  is  always  directed  to  the 
common  good  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  law  is  not  always  directed 
to  the  common  good  as  to  its  end.  For  it  belongs  to  law 
to  command  and  to  forbid.  But  commands  are  directed  to 
certain  individual  goods.  Therefore  the  end  of  the  law  is 
not  always  the  common  good. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  law  directs  man  in  his  actions.  But 
human  actions  are  concerned  with  particular  matters. 
Therefore  the  law  is  directed  to  some  particular  good. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Isidore  says  [Etym.  ii.) :  If  the  law  is  based 
on  reason,  whatever  is  based  on  reason  will  be  a  law.  But 
reason  is  the  foundation  not  only  of  what  is  ordained  to  the 
common  good,  but  also  of  that  which  is  directed  to  private 
good.  Therefore  the  law  is  not  only  directed  to  the  good  of 
all,  but  also  to  the  private  good  of  an  individual. 

On  the  contrary,  Isidore  says  (Etym.  v.)  that  laws  are  enacted 
for  no  private  profit,  but  for  the  common  benefit  of  the  citizens. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  the  law  belongs  to 
that  which  is  a  principle  of  human  acts,  because  it  is  their 
rule  and  measure.  Now  as  reason  is  a  principle  of  human 
acts,  so  in  reason  itself  there  is  something  which  is  the 
principle  in  respect  of  all  the  rest :  wherefore  to  this  principle 
chiefly  and  mainly  law  must  needs  be  referred. — Now  the 
first  principle  in  practical  matters,  which  are  the  object  of 
the  practical  reason,  is  the  last  end:  and  the  last  end  of 
human  life  is  bliss  or  happiness,  as  stated  above  (Q.  II.,  A.  7; 
Q.  III.,  A.  i).  Consequently  the  law  must  needs  regard 
principally  the  relationship  to  happiness.  ||  Moreover,  since 
every  part  is  ordained  to  the  whole,  as  imperfect  to  perfect ; 
and  since  one  man  is  a  part  of  the  perfect  community,  the 
law  must  needs  regard  properly  the  relationship  to  universal 
happiness.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher,  in  the  above 
definition  of  legal  matters  mentions  both  happiness  and  the 


5  THE  ESSENCE  OF  LAW         Q.  90.  Art.  2 

body  politic:  for  he  says  (Ethic,  v.)  that  we  call  those  legal 
matters  just,  which  are  adapted  to  produce  and  preserve  happi- 
ness and  its  parts  for  the  body  politic  :  since  the  state  is  a 
perfect  community,  as  he  says  in  Polit.  i. 

Now  in  every  genus,  that  which  belongs  to  it  chiefly  is  the 
principle  of  the  others,  and  the  others  belong  to  that  genus 
in  subordination  to  that  thing:  thus  fire,  which  is  chief 
among  hot  things,  is  the  cause  of  heat  in  mixed  bodies,  and 
these  are  said  to  be  hot  in  so  far  as  they  have  a  share  of  tire. 
Consequently,  since  the  law  is  chiefly  ordained  to  the  common 
good,  any  other  precept  in  regard  to  some  individual  work, 
must  needs  be  devoid  of  the  nature  of  a  law,  save  in  so  far 
as  it  regards  the  common  good.  Therefore  every  law  is 
ordained  to  the  common  good. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  A  command  denotes  an  application  of  a  law 
to  matters  regulated  by  the  law.  Now  the  order  to  the 
common  good,  at  which  the  law  aims,  is  applicable  to  par- 
ticular ends.  And  in  this  way  commands  are  given  even 
concerning  particular  matters. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Actions  are  indeed  concerned  with  particular 
matters:  but  those  particular  matters  are  referable  to  the 
common  good,  not  as  to  a  common  genus  or  species,  but  as 
to  a  common  final  cause,  according  as  the  common  good  is 
said  to  be  the  common  end. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Just  as  nothing  stands  firm  with  regard  to 
the  speculative  reason  except  that  which  is  traced  back  to 
the  hrst  indemonstrable  principles,  so  nothing  stands  firm 
with  regard  to  the  practical  reason,  unless  it  be  directed  to 
the  last  end  which  is  the  common  good:  and  whatever  stands 
to  reason  in  this  sense,  has  the  nature  of  a  law. 

Third  Article. 

whether  the  reason  of  any  man  is  competent 
to  make  laws  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 
Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  reason  of  any  man  is  compe- 
tent to  make  laws.     For  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  ii    14)  that 


Q.  90.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  6 

when  the  Gentiles,  who  have  not  the  law,  do  by  nature  those 
thing  that  are  of  the  law,  .  .  .  they  are  a  law  to  themselves. 
Now  he  says  this  of  all  in  general.  Therefore  anyone  can 
make  a  law  for  himself. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  ii.),  the 
intention  of  the  lawgiver  is  to  lead  men  to  virtue.  But  every 
man  can  lead  another  to  virtue.  Therefore  the  reason  of 
any  man  is  competent  to  make  laws. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  just  as  the  sovereign  of  a  state  governs 
the  state,  so  every  father  of  a  family  governs  his  household. 
But  the  sovereign  of  a  state  can  make  laws  for  the  state. 
Therefore  every  father  of  a  family  can  make  laws  for  his 
household. 

On  the  contrary,  Isidore  says  [Etym.  v. ;  and  the  passage  is 
quoted  in  Decretals,  Dist.  2) :  A  law  is  an  ordinance  of  the 
people,  whereby  somethijtg  is  sanctioned  by  the  Elders  together 
with  the  Commonalty. 

I  answer  that,  A  law,  properly  speaking,  regards  first  and 
foremost  the  order  to  the  common  good.  Now  to  order 
anything  to  the  common  good,  belongs  either  to  the  whole 
people,  or  to  someone  who  is  the  vicegerent  of  the  whole 
people.  And  therefore  the  making  of  a  law  belongs  either 
to  the  whole  people  or  to  a  public  personage  who  has  care 
of  the  whole  people :  since  in  all  other  matters  the  directing 
of  anything  to  the  end  concerns  him  to  whom  the  end 
belongs. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  As  stated  above  (.4.  1  ad  1),  3.  law  is  in  a 
person  not  only  as  in  one  that  rules,  but  also  by  participa- 
tion as  in  one  that  is  ruled.  In  the  latter  way  each  one  is  a 
law  to  himself,  in  so  far  as  he  shares  the  direction  that  he 
receives  from  one  who  rules  him.  Hence  the  same  text 
goes  on :  Who  show  the  work  of  the  law  written  in  their  hearts. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  A  private  person  cannot  lead  another  to 
virtue  efficaciously:  for  he  can  only  advise,  and  if  his  advice 
be  not  taken,  it  has  no  coercive  power,  such  as  the  law  should 
have,  in  order  to  prove  an  efficacious  inducement  to  virtue, 
as  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  x.).  But  this  coercive  power 
is  vested  in  the  whole  people  or  in  some  public  personage, 


7  THE  ESSENCE  OF  LAW        Q-  90.  Art.  4 

to  whom  it  belongs  to  inflict  penalties,  as  we  shall  state 
further  on  (Q.  XCIL,  A.  2  ad  3;  II.-IL,  Q.  LXIV.,  A.  3). 
Wherefore  the  framing  of  laws  belongs  to  him  alone. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  one  man  is  a  part  of  the  household,  so  a 
household  is  a  part  of  the  state:  and  the  state  is  a  perfect 
community,  according  to  Polit.  i.  And  therefore,  as  the 
good  of  one  man  is  not  the  last  end,  but  is  ordained  to  the 
common  good ;  so  too  the  good  of  one  household  is  ordained 
to  the  good  of  a  single  state,  which  is  a  perfect  community. 
Consequently  he  that  governs  a  family,  can  indeed  make 
certain  commands  or  ordinances,  but  not  such  as  to  have 
properly  the  force  of  law. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  promulgation  is  essential  to  a  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  promulgation  is  not  essential 
to  a  law.  For  the  natural  law  above  all  has  the  character 
of  law.  But  the  natural  law  needs  no  promulgation. 
Therefore  it  is  not  essential  to  a  law  that  it  be  promulgated. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  it  belongs  properly  to  a  law  to  bind  one 
to  do  or  not  to  do  sormething.  But  the  obligation  of  ful- 
filling a  law  touches  not  only  those  in  whose  presence  it  is 
promulgated,  but  also  others.  Therefore  promulgation  is 
not  essential  to  a  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  binding  force  of  a  law  extends  even 
to  the  future,  since  laws  arc  binding  in  matters  of  the  futtire, 
as  the  jurists  say  [Cod.  i.,  tit.  De  lege  et  constit.).  But  pro- 
mulgation concerns  those  who  are  present.  Therefore  it  is 
not  essential  to  a  law. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  laid  down  in  the  Decretals  (Append. 
Grat.)  that  laws  are  established  when  they  are  promulgated. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  a  law  is  imposed  on 
others  by  way  of  a  rule  and  measure.  Now  a  rule  or  measure 
is  imposed  by  being  applied  to  those  who  are  to  be  ruled  and 
measured  by  it.  Wherefore,  in  order  that  a  law  obtain  the 
binding  force  which  is  proper  to  a  law,  it  must  needs  be~ 


Q.  90.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  8 

applied  to  the  men  who  have  to  be  ruled  by  it.  Such 
application  is  made  by  its  being  notified  to  them  by  pro- 
mulgation. Wherefore  promulgation  is  necessary  for  the 
law  to  obtain  its  force. 

Thus  from  the  four  preceding  articles,  the  definition  of  law 
may  be  gathered;  and  it  is  nothing  else  than  "an  ordinance  of 
reason"^lor  the  common  good/ made  by  him  who  has  care  of 
the  community;  and  promulgated. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  natural  law  is  promulgated  by  the  very 
fact  that  God  instilled  it  into  man's  mind  so  as  to  be  known 
by  him  naturally. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Those  who  are  not  present  when  a  law  is  pro- 
mulgated, are  bound  to  observe  the  law,  in  so  far  as  it  is 
notified  or  can  be  notified  to  them  by  others,  after  it  has 
been  promulgated. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  promulgation  that  takes  place  now, 
extends  to  future  time  by  reason  of  the  durability  of  written 
characters,  by  which  means  it  is  continually  promulgated. 
Hence  Isidore  says  [Etym.  ii.)  that  lex  (law)  is  derived  from 
legere  (to  read)  hecause  it  is  written. 


QUESTION  XCI. 

OF  THE  VARIOUS  KINDS  OF  LAW. 

{In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  various  kinds  of  law:  under 
which  head  there  are  six  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  there 
is  an  eternal  law  ?  (2)  Whether  there  is  a  natural  law  ? 
(3)  Whether  there  is  a  human  law  ?  (4)  Whether  there  is  a 
Divine  law  ?  (5)  Whether  there  is  one  Divine  law,  or 
several  ?     (6)  Whether  there  is  a  law  of  sin  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  there  is  an  eternal  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  is  no  eternal  law.  Because 
every  law  is  imposed  on  someone.  But  there  was  not  some- 
one from  eternity  on  whom  a  law  could  be  imposed:  since 
God  alone  was  from  eternity.     Therefore  no  law  is  eternal. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  promulgation  is  essential  to  law.  But 
promulgation  could  not  be  from  eternity :  because  there  was 
no  one  to  whom  it  could  be  promulgated  from  eternity. 
Therefore  no  law  can  be  eternal. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  a  law  implies  order  to  an  end.  But 
nothing  ordained  to  an  end  is  eternal:  for  the  last  end  alone 
is  eternal.     Therefore  no  law  is  eternal. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Lib.  Arb.  i.) :  That 
Law  which  is  the  Supreme  Reason  cannot  be  understood  to  be 
otherwise  than  unchangeable  and  eternal. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  K.  1  ad  2\  AA. 
3,  4),  a  law  is  nothing  else  but  a  dictate  of  practical  reason 

9 


Q.  91 .  Art.  i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  10 

emanating  from  the  ruler  who  governs  a  perfect  community. 
Now  it  is  evident,  granted  that  the  world  is  ruled  by  Divine 
Providence,  as  was  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XXII., 
A  A.  I,  2),  that  the  whole  community  of  the  universe  is 
governed  by  Divine  Reason.  Wherefore  the  very  Idea  of 
the  government  of  things  in  God  the  Ruler  of  the  universe, 
has  the  nature  of  a  law.  And  since  the  Divine  Reason's  con- 
ception of  things  is  not  subject  to  time  but  is  eternal, 
according  to  Prov.  viii.  23,  therefore  it  is  that  this  kind  of 
law  must  be  called  eternal. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Those  things  that  are  not  in  themselves, 
exist  with  God,  inasmuch  as  they  are  foreknown  and  pre- 
ordained by  Him,  according  to  Rom.  iv.  17 :  Who  calls  those 
things  that  are  not,  as  those  that  are.  Accordingly  the  eternal 
concept  of  the  Divine  law  bears  the  character  of  an  eternal 
law,  in  so  far  as  it  is  ordained  by  God  to  the  government  of 
things  foreknown  by  Him. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Promulgation  is  made  by  word  of  mouth  or 
in  writing ;  and  in  both  ways  the  eternal  law  is  promulgated : 
because  both  the  Divine  Word  and  the  writing  of  the  Book 
of  Life  are  eternal.  But  the  promulgation  cannot  be  from 
eternity  on  the  part  of  the  creature  that  hears  or  reads. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  law  implies  order  to  the  end  actively, 
in  so  far  as  it  directs  certain  things  to  the  end;  but  not 
passively, — that  is  to  say,  the  law  itself  is  not  ordained  to 
the  end, — except  accidentally,  in  a  governor  whose  end  is 
extrinsic  to  him,  and  to  which  end  his  law  must  needs  be 
ordained.  But  the  end  of  the  Divine  government  is  God 
Himself,  and  His  law  is  not  distinct  from  Himself.  Where- 
fore the  eternal  law  is  not  ordained  to  another  end. 

Second  Article, 
whether  there  is  in  us  a  natural  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Ohjection  1.  It  seems  that  there  is  no  natural  law  in  us. 
Because  man  is  governed  sufficiently  by  the  eternal  law: 
for  Augustine  says  (De  Lib.  Arh.  i.)  that  the  eternal  law  is  that 


II  THE  VARIOUS  KINDS  OF  LAW     Q.  91.  Am.  2 

by  which  it  is  right  that  all  things  should  he  most  orderly.  But 
nature  does  not  abound  in  supcrlluities  as  neither  does  she 
fail  in  necessaries.     Therefore  no  law  is  natural  to  man. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  by  the  law  man  is  directed,  in  his  acts,  to 
the  end,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2).  But  the  directing  of 
human  acts  to  their  end  is  not  a  function  of  nature,  as  is  the 
case  in  irrational  creatures,  which  act  for  an  end  solely  by 
their  natural  appetite ;  whereas  man  acts  for  an  end  by  his 
reason  and  will.     Therefore  no  law  is  natural  to  man. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  more  a  man  is  free,  the  less  is  he  under 
the  law.  But  man  is  freer  than  all  the  animals,  on  account 
of  his  free-will,  with  which  he  is  endowed  above  all  other 
animals.  Since  therefore  other  animals  are  not  subject  to  a 
natural  law,  neither  is  man  subject  to  a  natural  law. 

On  the  contrary,  The  gloss  on  Rom.  ii.  14:  When  the  Gentiles, 
who  have  not  the  law,  do  by  nature  those  things  that  are  of  the 
law,  comments  as  follows:  Although  they  have  no  written 
law,  yet  they  have  the  natural  law,  whereby  each  one  knows,  and 
is  conscious  of,  what  is  good  and  what  is  evil. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  i  ad  1),  law, 
being  a  rule  and  measure,  can  be  in  a  person  in  two  ways :  in 
one  way,  as  in  him  that  rules  and  measures ;  in  another  way, 
as  in  that  which  is  ruled  and  measured,  since  a  thing  is  ruled 
and  measured,  in  so  far  as  it  partakes  of  the  rule  or  measure. 
Wherefore,  since  all  things  subject  to  Divine  providence  are 
ruled  and  measured  by  the  eternal  law,  as  was  stated  above 
(A.  i);  it  is  evident  that  ah  things  partake  somewhat  of  the 
eternal  law,  in  so  far  as,  namely,  from  its  being  imprinted 
on  them,  they  derive  their  respective  inclinations  to  their 
proper  acts  and  ends.  Now  among  all  others,  the  ^rational 
creature  is  subject  to  Divine  providence  in  the  most  excellent 
way,  in  so  far  as  it  partakes  of  a  share  of  providence,  by 
being  piovideiU  l^olh  for  itself  and  for  others.  Wherefore 
it  has  a  share  of  the  Eternal  Reason,  whereby  it  has  a  natural 
inchnation  to  its  proper  act  and  end:  and  this  2^^i£i£5ii2IL 
of  the  eternal  law  in  the  rational  creature  is  called  the 
natural  law.  Hence  the  Psalmist  after  saying  (Ps.  iv.  6) : 
Offer  up  the  sacrifice  of  justice,  as  though  someone  asked 


Q.  91 .  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  12 

what  the  works  of  justice  are,  adds:  Many  say,  Who  showeth 
us  good  things?  in  answer  to  which  question  he  says:  The 
light  of  Thy  countenance,  0  Lord,  is  signed  upon  us :  thus 
implying  that  the  light  of  natural  reason,  whereby  we 
discern  what  is  good  and  what  is  evil,  which  is  the  function 
of  the  natural  law,  is  nothing  else  than  an  imprint  on  us 
of  the  Divine  light.  It  is  therefore  evident  that  the  natural 
law  is  nothing  else  than  the  rational  creature's  participation 
of  the  eternal  law. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  argument  would  hold,  if  the  natural 
law  were  something  different  from  the  eternal  law :  whereas 
it  is  nothing  but  a  participation  thereof,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Every  act  of  reason  and  will  in  us  is  based 
on  that  which  is  according  to  nature,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  X.,  A.  i) :  for  every  act  of  reasoning  is  based  on  principles 
that  are  known  naturally,  and  every  act  of  appetite  in 
respect  of  the  means  is  derived  from  the  natural  appetite  in 
respect  of  the  last  end.  Accordingly  the  first  direction  of 
our  acts  to  their  end  must  needs  be  in  virtue  of  the  natural 
law. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Even  irrational  animals  partake  in  their 
own  way  of  the  Eternal  Reason,  just  as  the  rational  creature 
does.  But  because  the  rational  creature  partakes  thereof 
in  an  intellectual  and  rational  manner,  therefore  the  par- 
ticipation of  the  eternal  law  in  the  rational  creature  is 
properly  called  a  law,  since  a  law  is  something  pertaining  to 
reason,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  i).  Irrational  creatures, 
however,  do  not  partake  thereof  in  a  rational  manner, 
wherefore  there  is  no  participation  of  the  eternal  law  in 
them,  except  by  way  of  similitude. 

Third  Article, 
whether  there  is  a  human  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  there  is  not  a  human  law.  For 
the  natural  law  is  a  participation  of  the  eternal  law,  as 
stated  above  (A.  2).     Now  through  the  eternal  law  all  things 


13 


THE  VARIOUS  KINDS  OF  LAW    Q.  91.  Art.  3 


are  most  orderly,  as  Augustine  states  {De  Lib.  Arb.  i.). 
Therefore  the  natural  law  suffices  for  the  ordering  of  all 
human  affairs.  Consequently  there  is  no  need  for  a  human 
law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  a  law  bears  the  character  of  a  measure, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  i).  But  human  reason  is  not  a 
measure  of  things,  but  vice  versa  (c/.  Metaph.  x.).  Therefore 
no  law  can  emanate  from  human  reason. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  a  measure  should  be  most  certain,  as 
stated  in  Metaph.  x.  But  the  dictates  of  human  reason  in 
matters  of  conduct  are  uncertain,  according  to  Wis.  ix.  14: 
The  thoughts  of  mortal  men  are  fearful,  and  our  counsels 
uncertain.  Therefore  no  law  can  emanate  from  human 
reason. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  {De  Lib.  Arb.  i.)  distinguishes 
two  kinds  of  law,  the  one  eternal,  the  other  temporal,  which 
he  calls  human. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  i,  ai  2),  a  law 
is  a  dictate  of  the  practical  reason.  Now  it  is  to  be  observed 
that  the  same  procedure  takes  place  in  the  practical  and  in 
the  speculative  reason:  for  each  proceeds  from  principles  to 
conclusions,  as  stated  above  [ibid.).  Accordingly  we  con- 
clude that  just  as,  in  the  speculative  reason,  from  naturally 
known  indemonstrable  principles,  we  draw  the  conclusions 
of  the  various  sciences,  the  knowledge  of  which  is  not  im- 
parted to  us  by  nature,  but  acquired  by  the  efforts  of  reason, 
so  too  it  is  from  the  precepts  of  the  natural  law,  as  from 
general  and  indemonstrable  principles,  that  the  human 
reason  needs  to  proceed  to  the  more  particular  determination  i 
of  certain  matters.  These  particular  determinations,  devised 
by  human  reason,  are  called  human  laws,  provided  the  other 
essential  conditions  of  law  be  observed,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XC,  A  A.  2,  3,  4).  Wherefore  Tully  says  in  his  Rhetoric 
{De  Invent.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  justice  has  its  source  in  nature  ; 
thence  certain  things  came  into  custom  by  reason  of  their  utility  ; 
afterwards  these  things  which  emanated  from  nature  and  were 
approved  by  custom,  were  sanctioned  by  fear  and  reverence  for 
the  law. 


Q.  91.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  14 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  human  reason  cannot  have  a  full  par- 
ticipation of  the  dictate  of  the  Divine  Reason,  but  according 
to  its  own  mode,  and  imperfectly.  Consequently,  as  on  the 
part  of  the  speculative  reason,  by  a  natural  participation  of 
Divine  Wisdom,  there  is  in  us  the  knowledge  of  certain 
general  principles,  but  not  proper  knowledge  of  each  single 
truth,  such  as  that  contained  in  the  Divine  Wisdom ;  so  too, 
on  the  part  of  the  practical  reason,  man  has  a  natural  par- 
ticipation of  the  eternal  law,  according  to  certain  general 
principles,  but  not  as  regards  the  particular  determinations 
of  individual  cases,  which  are,  however,  contained  in  the 
eternal  law.  Hence  the  need  for  human  reason  to  proceed 
further  to  sanction  them  by  law. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Human  reason  is  not,  of  itself,  the  rule  of 
things:  but  the  principles  impressed  on  it  by  nature,  are 
general  rules  and  measures  of  all  things  relating  to  human 
conduct,  whereof  the  natural  reason  is  the  rule  and  measure, 
although  it  is  not  the  measure  of  things  that  are  from 
nature. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  practical  reason  is  concerned  with 
practical  matters,  which  are  singular  and  contingent:  but 
not  with  necessary  things,  with  which  the  speculative  reason 
is  concerned.  Wherefore  human  laws  cannot  have  that 
inerrancy  that  belongs  to  the  demonstrated  conclusions  of 
sciences.  Nor  is  it  necessary  for  every  measure  to  be  alto- 
gether unerring  and  certain, but  according  as  it  is  possible  in 
its  own  particular  genus. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  there  was  any  need  for  a  divine  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  there  was  no  need  for  a  Divine 
law.  Because,  as  stated  above  (A.  2),  the  natural  law  is  a 
participation  in  us  of  the  eternal  law.  But  the  eternal  law  is 
a  Divine  law,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  Therefore  there  is  no 
need  for  a  Divine  law  in  addition  to  the  natural  law,  and 
human  laws  derived  therefrom. 


15  THE  VARIOUS  KINDS  OF  LAW    Q.9T.ART.4 

Obj.  2.  Further,  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  xv.  14)  that  God 
left  man  in  the  hand  of  his  own  counsel.  Now  counsel  is  an 
act  of  reason,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XIV.,  A.  i).  Therefore 
man  was  left  to  the  direction  of  his  reason.  But  a  dictate 
of  human  reason  is  a  human  law,  as  stated  above  (A.  3). 
Therefore  there  is  no  need  for  man  to  be  governed  also  by  a 
Divine  law. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  human  nature  is  more  self-sufficing  than 
irrational  creatures.  But  irrational  creatures  have  no 
Divine  law  besides  the  natural  inclination  impressed  on  them. 
Much  less,  therefore,  should  the  rational  creature  have  a 
Divine  law  in  addition  to  the  natural  law. 

On  the  contrary,  David  prayed  God  to  set  His  law  before 
him,  saying:  Set  before  me  for  a  law  the  way  of  Thy  justifica- 
tions, 0  Lord. 

I  answer  that.  Besides  the  natural  and  the  human  law  it 
was  necessary  for  the  directing  of  human  conduct  to  have  a 
Divine  law.  And  this  for  four  reasons.  First,  because  it 
is  by  law  that  man  is  directed  how  to  perform  his  proper  acts 
in  view  of  his  last  end.  And  indeed  if  man  were  ordained  to 
no  other  end  than  that  which  is  proportionate  to  his  natural 
faculty,  there  would  be  no  need  for  man  to  have  any  further 
direction  on  the  part  of  his  reason,  besides  the  natural  law 
and  human  law  which  is  derived  from  it.  But  since  man  is 
ordained  to  an  end  of  eternal  happiness  which  is  inpro- 
portionate  to  man's  natural  faculty,  as  stated  above  (0.  V., 
A.  5),  therefore  it  was  necessary  that,  besides  the  natural 
and  the  human  law,  man  should  be  directed  to  his  end  by  a_ 
law  given  by  God.JT/  'if  ■  •^'"'    / 

Secondly,  because,  on  account  of  the  uncertainty  of 
human  judgment,  especially  on  contingent  and  particular 
matters,  different  people  form  different  judgments  on  human 
acts;  whence  also  different  and  contrary  laws  result.  In 
order,  therefore,  that  man  may  know  without  any  doubt 
what  he  ought  to  do  and  what  he  ought  to  avoid,  it  was 
necessary  for  man  to  be  directed  in  his  proper  acts  by  a  law 
given  by  God,  for  it  is  certain  that  such  a  law  cannot  err. 

Thirdly,  because  man  can  make  laws  in  those  matters  of 


Q.  91.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  16 

which  he  is  competent  to  judge.  But  man  is  not  competent 
to  judge  of  interior  movements,  that  are  hidden,  but  only  of 
exterior  acts  which  appear:  and  yet  for  the  perfection  of 
virtue  it  is  necessary  for  man  to  conduct  himself  aright  in 
both  kinds  of  acts.  Consequently  human  law  could  not 
sufficiently  curb  and  direct  interior  acts ;  and  it  was  necessary 
for  this  purpose  that  a  Divine  law  should  supervene. 

Fourthly,  because,  as  Augustine  says  (De  Lib.  Arb.  i.), 
human  law  cannot  punish  or  forbid  all  evil  deeds:  since 
while  aiming  at  doing  away  with  all  evils,  it  would  do  away 
with  many  good  things,  and  would  hinder  the  advance  of 
the  common  good,  which  is  necessary  for  human  intercourse. 
In  order,  therefore,  that  no  evil  might  remain  unforbidden 
and  unpunished,  it  was  necessary  for  the  Divine  law  to  super- 
vene, whereby  all  sins  are  forbidden. 

And  these  four  causes  are  touched  upon  in  Ps.  cxviii.  8, 
where  it  is  said:  The  law  of  the  Lord  is  unspotted,  i.e.,  allowing 
no  foulness  of  sin;  converting  souls,  because  it  directs  not 
only  exterior,  but  also  interior  acts ;  the  testimony  of  the  Lord 
is  faithful,  because  of  the  certainty  of  what  is  true  and  right ; 
giving  wisdom  to  little  ones,  by  directing  man  to  an  end  super- 
natural and  Divine. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  By  the  natural  law  the  eternal  law  is  par- 
ticipated proportionately  to  the  capacity  of  human  nature. 
But  to  his  supernatural  end  man  needs  to  be  directed  in  a 
yet  higher  way.  Hence  the  additional  law  given  by  God, 
whereby  man  shares  more  perfectly  in  the  eternal  law. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Counsel  is  a  kind  of  inquiry:  hence  it  must 
proceed  from  some  principles.  Nor  is  it  enough  for  it  to 
proceed  from  principles  imparted  by  nature,  which  are  the 
precepts  of  the  natural  law,  for  the  reasons  given  above: 
but  there  is  need  for  certain  additional  principles,  namely, 
the  precepts  of  the  Divine  law. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Irrational  creatures  are  not  ordained  to  an 
end  higher  than  that  which  is  proportionate  to  their  natural 
powers:  consequently  the  comparison  fails. 


17  THE  VARIOUS  KINDS  OF  LAW    Q.^jlAkto 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  there  is  but  one  divine  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  is  but  one  Divine  law. 
Because,  where  there  is  one  king  in  one  kingdom  there  is 
but  one  law.  Now  the  whole  of  mankind  is  compared  to 
God  as  to  one  king,  according  to  Ps.  xlvi.  8 :  God  is  the  King 
of  all  the  earth.     Therefore  there  is  but  one  Divine  law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  every  law  is  directed  to  the  end  which 
the  lawgiver  intends  for  those  for  whom  he  makes  the  law. 
But  God  intends  one  and  the  same  thing  for  all  men;  since 
according  to  i  Tim.  ii.  4:  He  will  have  all  men  to  be  saved, 
and  to  come  to  the  knowledge  of  the  truth.  Therefore  there  is 
but  one  Divine  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Divine  law  seems  to  be  more  akin  to 
the  eternal  law,  which  is  one,  than  the  natural  law,  according 
as  the  revelation  of  grace  is  of  a  higher  order  than  natural 
knowledge.     Therefore  much  more  is  the  Divine  law  but  one. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Heb.  vii.  12) :  The  priest- 
hood being  translated,  it  is  necessary  that  a  translation  also  be 
made  of  the  law.  But  the  priesthood  is  twofold,  as  stated 
in  the  same  passage,  viz.,  the  levitical  priesthood,  and  the 
priesthood  of  Christ.  Therefore  the  Divine  law  is  twofold, 
namely,  the  Old  Law  and  the  New  Law. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XXX.,  A.  3), 
distinction  is  the  cause  of  number.  Now  things  may  be 
distinguished  in  two  ways.  First,  as  those  things  that  are 
altogether  specifically  different,  e.g.,  a  horse  and  an  ox. 
Secondly,  as  perfect  and  imperfect  in  the  same  species, 
e.g.,  a  boy  and  a  man:  and  in  this  way  the  Divine  law  is 
divided  into  Old  and  New.  Hence  the  Apostle  (Gal.  iii. 
24,  25)  compares  the  state  of  man  under  the  Old  Law  to 
that  of  a  child  under  a  pedagogue  ;  but  the  state  under  the 
New  Law,  to  that  of  a  full  grown  man,  who  is  no  longer  under 
a  pedagogue. 

Now  the  perfection  and  imperfection  of  these  two  laws 
II.  3  2 


Q.  91 .  Art.  5    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  18 

is  to  be  taken  in  connection  with  the  three  conditions  per- 
taining to  law,  as  stated  above.  For,  in  the  first  place,  it 
belongs  to  law  to  be  directed  to  the  common  good  as  to  its 
end,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2).  This  good  may  be 
twofold.  It  may  be  a  sensible  and  earthly  good;  and  to 
this,  man  was  directly  ordained  l:)y  the  Old  Law:  wherefore, 
at  the  very  outset  of  the  law,  the  people  were  invited  to  the 
earthly  kingdom  of  the  Chananseans  (Exod.  iii.  8,  17). 
Again  it  may  be  an  intelligible  and  heavenly  good:  and  to 
this,  man  is  ordained  by  the  New  Law.  Wherefore,  at  the 
very  beginning  of  His  preaching,  Christ  invited  men  to  the 
kingdom  of  heaven,  saying  (Matth.  iv.  17) :  Do  penance,  for 
the  kingdom  of  heaven  is  at  hand.  Hence  Augustine  says 
{Contra  Faust,  iv.)  that  promises  of  temporal  goods  are  con- 
tained in  the  Old  Testament,  for  which  reason  it  is  called  old  ; 
hut  the  promise  of  eternal  life  belongs  to  the  New  Testament. 

Secondly,  it  belongs  to  the  law  to  direct  human  acts 
according  to  the  order  of  righteousness  (A.  4) :  wherein  also 
the  New  Law  surpasses  the  Old  Law,  since  it  directs  our 
internal  acts,  according  to  Matth.  v.  20:  Unless  your  justice 
abound  more  than  that  of  the  Scribes  and  Pharisees,  you  shall 
not  enter  into  the  kingdom  of  heaven.  Hence  the  saying  that 
the  Old  Law  restrains  the  hand,  but  the  New  Law  controls  the 
mind  (3  Sentent.,  dist.  xL). 

Thirdly,  it  belongs  to  the  law  to  induce  men  to  observe 
its  commandments.  This  the  Old  Law  did  by  the  fear  of 
punishment :  but  the  New  Law,  by  love,  which  is  poured  into 
our  hearts  by  the  grace  of  Christ,  bestowed  in  the  New  Law, 
but  foreshadowed  in  the  Old.  Hence  Augustine  says 
[Contra  Adimant.  Manich.  discip.  xvii.)  that  in  a  word  the 
difference  between  the  Law  and  the  Gospel  is  this — fear  and 
love. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  As  the  father  of  a  family  issues  different 
commands  to  the  children  and  to  the  adults,  so  also  the  one 
King,  God,  in  His  one  kingdom,  gave  one  law  to  men,  while 
they  were  yet  imperfect,  and  another  more  perfect  law, 
when,  by  the  preceding  law,  they  had  been  led  to  a  greater 
capacity  for  Divine  things. 


19  THE  VARIOUS  KINDS  OF  LAW       QoiArtG 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  salvation  of  man  could  not  be  achieved 
otherwise  than  through  Christ,  according  to  Acts  iv.  12: 
There  is  no  other  name  .  .  .  given  to  men,  whereby  we  must  be 
saved.  Consequently  the  law  that  brings  all  to  salvation 
could  not  be  given  until  after  the  coming  of  Christ.  But 
before  His  coming  it  was  necessary  to  give  to  the  people,  of 
whom  Christ  was  to  be  born,  a  law  containing  certain  rudi- 
ments of  righteousness  unto  salvation,  in  order  to  prepare 
them  to  receive  Him. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  natural  law  directs  man  by  way  of 
certain  general  precepts,  common  to  both  the  perfect  and  the 
imperfect:  wherefore  it  is  one  and  the  same  for  all.  But  the 
Divine  law  directs  man  also  in  certain  particular  matters,  to 
which  the  perfect  and  imperfect  do  not  stand  in  the  same 
relation.  Hence  the  necessity  for  the  Divine  law  to  be 
twofold,  as  already  explained. 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  there  is  a  law  in  the  fomes  of  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  is  no  law  of  the  '  fomes  ' 
of  sin.  For  Isidore  says  (Etym.  v.)  that  the  law  is  based  on 
reason.  But  the  '  fomes '  of  sin  is  not  based  on  reason,  but 
deviates  from  it.  Therefore  the  *  fomes  '  has  not  the  nature 
of  a  law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  every  law  is  binding,  so  that  those  who 
do  not  obey  it  are  called  transgressors.  But  man  is  not 
called  a  transgressor,  from  not  following  the  instigations  of 
the  '  fomes  ' ;  but  rather  from  his  following  them.  Therefore 
the  '  fomes '  has  not  the  nature  of  a  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  law  is  ordained  to  the  common  good, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2).  But  the  *  fomes '  inclines  us, 
not  to  the  common,  but  to  our  own  private  good.  Therefore 
the  '  fomes '  has  not  the  nature  of  sin. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  vii.  23) :  /  sec 
another  law  in  my  members,  fighting  against  the  law  of  my 
mind. 


Q.  91.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  20 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  2;  Q.  XC,  A.  i  ad  i), 
the  law,  as  to  its  essence,  resides  in  him  that  rules  and 
measures;  but,  by  way  of  participation,  in  that  which  is 
ruled  and  measured;  so  that  every  inclination  or  ordination 
which  may  be  found  in  things  subject  to  the  law,  is  called  a 
law  by  participation,  as  stated  above  (ibid.).  Now  those 
who  are  subject  to  a  law  may  receive  a  twofold  inclination 
from  the  lawgiver.  First,  in  so  far  as  he  directly  inclines  his 
subjects  to  something;  sometimes  indeed  different  subjects 
to  different  acts;  in  this  way  we  may  say  that  there  is  a 
military  law  and  a  mercantile  law.  Secondly,  indirectly; 
thus  by  the  very  fact  that  a  lawgiver  deprives  a  subject  of 
some  dignity,  the  latter  passes  into  another  order,  so  as  to 
be  imder  another  law,  as  it  were :  thus  if  a  soldier  be  turned 
out  of  the  army,  he  becomes  a  subject  of  rural  or  of  mercan- 
tile legislation. 

Accordingly  under  the  Divine  Lawgiver  various  creatures 
have  various  natural  inclinations,  so  that  what  is,  as 
it  were,  a  law  for  one,  is  against  the  law  for  another: 
thus  I  might  say  that  fierceness  is,  in  a  way,  the  law 
of  a  dog,  but  against  the  law  of  a  sheep  or  another  meek 
animal.  And  so  the  law  of  man,  which,  by  the  Divine 
ordinance,  is  allotted  to  him,  according  to  his  proper  natural 
condition,  is  that  he  should  act  in  accordance  with  reason: 
and  this  law  was  so  effective  in  the  primitive  state,  that 
nothing  either  beside  or  against  reason  could  take  man 
unawares.  But  when  man  turned  his  back  on  God,  he  fell 
under  the  influence  of  his  sensual  impulses :  in  fact  this  hap- 
pens to  each  one  individually,  the  more  he  deviates  from 
the  path  of  reason,  so  that,  after  a  fashion,  he  is  likened  to 
the  beasts  that  are  led  by  the  impulse  of  sensuahty,  according 
to  Ps.  xlviii.  21:  Man,  when  he  was  in  honour,  did  not  under- 
stand :  he  hath  been  compared  to  senseless  beasts,  and  made 
like  to  them. 

So,  then,  this  very  inclination  of  sensuality  which  is  called 
the  *  fomes,'  in  other  animals  has  simply  the  nature  of  a  law, 
(yet  only  in  so  far  as  a  law  may  be  said  to  be  in  such  things), 
by  reason  of  a  direct  inclination.     But  in  man,  it  has  not 


21  THE  VARIOUS  KINDS  OF  LAW   Q.  91.  Art.  6 

the  nature  of  law  in  this  way,  rather  is  it  a  deviation  from 
the  law  of  reason.  But  since,  by  the  just  sentence  of  God, 
man  is  destitute  of  original  justice,  and  his  reason  bereft  of 
its  vigour,  this  impulse  of  sensuality,  whereby  he  is  led,  in  so 
far  as  it  is  a  penalty  following  from  the  Divine  law  depriving 
man  of  his  proper  dignity,  has  the  nature  of  a  law. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  This  argument  considers  the  *  fomes  '  in  itself , 
as  an  incentive  to  evil.  It  is  not  thus  that  it  has  the  nature 
of  a  law,  as  stated  above,  but  according  as  it  results  from 
the  justice  of  the  Divine  law:  it  is  as  though  we  were  to  say 
that  the  law  allows  a  nobleman  to  be  condemned  to  hard 
labour  for  some  misdeed. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  argument  considers  law  in  the  light 
of  a  rule  or  measure:  for  it  is  in  this  sense  that  those  who 
deviate  from  the  law  become  transgressors.  But  the  *  fomes ' 
is  not  a  law  in  this  respect,  but  by  a  kind  of  participation,  as 
stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  This  argument  considers  the  '  fomes  *  as  to 
its  proper  inclination,  and  not  as  to  its  origin.  And  yet  if 
the  inclination  of  sensuality  be  considered  as  it  is  in  other 
animals,  thus  it  is  ordained  to  the  common  good,  namely,  to 
the  preservation  of  nature  in  the  species  or  in  the  individual. 
And  this  is  in  man  also,  in  so  far  as  sensuality  is  subject  to 
reason.  But  it  is  called  the  '  fomes '  in  so  far  as  it  strays 
from  the  order  of  reason. 


QUESTION  XCII. 

OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  LAW. 

[In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  effects  of  law ;  under  which  head 
there  are  two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  an  effect  of  law 
is  to  make  men  good  ?  (2)  Whether  the  effects  of  law  are 
to  command,  to  forbid,  to  permit,  and  to  punish,  as  the 
Jurist  states  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  an  effect  of  law  is  to  make  men  good  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  it  is  not  an  effect  of  law  to  make 
men  good.  For  men  are  good  through  virtue,  since  virtue, 
as  stated  in  Ethic,  ii.  is  that  which  makes  its  subject  good. 
But  virtue  is  in  man  from  God  alone,  because  He  it  is  Who 
works  it  in  us  without  us,  as  we  stated  above  (Q.  LV.,  A.  4)  in 
giving  the  definition  of  virtue.  Therefore  the  law  does  not 
make  men  good. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Law  does  not  profit  a  man  unless  he 
obeys  it.  But  the  very  fact  that  a  man  obe^^s  a  law  is  due 
to  his  being  good.  Therefore  in  man  goodness  is  presup- 
posed to  the  law.    Therefore  the  law  does  not  make  men  good. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Law  is  ordained  to  the  common  good,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2).  But  some  behave  well  in 
things  regarding  the  community,  who  behave  ill  in  things 
regarding  themselves.  Therefore  it  is  not  the  business  of 
the  law  to  make  men  good. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  some  laws  are  tyrannical,  as  the  Philoso- 
pher says  [Polit.  iii.).     But  a  tyrant  does  not  intend  the 

22 


23  THE  EFFECTS  OF  LAW        Q.92.ART.  i 

good  of  his  subjects,  but  considers  only  his  own  profit. 
Therefore  law  does  not  make  men  good. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  ii.)  that  the 
intention  of  every  lawgiver  is  to  make  good  citizens. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  1  ad2\  A  A.  3,4), 
a  law  is  nothing  else  than  a  dictate  of  reason  in  the  ruler  by 
whom  his  subjects  are  governed.  Now  the  virtue  of  any 
subordinate  thing  consists  in  its  being  well  subordinated  to 
that  by  which  it  is  regulated :  thus  we  see  that  the  virtue  of 
the  irascible  and  concupiscible  faculties  consists  in  their 
being  obedient  to  reason ;  and  accordingly  the  virtue  of  every 
subject  consists  in  his  being  well  subjected  to  his  ruler,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  (Polit.  i.).  But  every  law  aims  at  being 
obeyed  by  those  who  are  subject  to  it.  Consequently  it  is 
evident  that  the  proper  effect  of  law  is  to  lead  its  subjects  to 
their  proper  virtue:  and  since  virtue  is  that  which  makes  its 
subject  good,  it  follows  that  the  proper  effect  of  law  is  to 
make  those  to  whom  it  is  given,  good,  either  simply  or  in 
some  particular  respect.  For  if  the  intention  of  the  law- 
giver is  fixed  on  true  good,  which  is  the  common  good  regu- 
lated according  to  Divine  justice,  it  follows  that  the  effect 
of  the  law  is  to  make  men  good  simply.  If,  however,  the 
intention  of  the  lawgiver  is  fixed  on  that  which  is  not  simply 
good,  but  useful  or  pleasurable  to  himself,  or  in  opposition 
to  Divine  justice;  then  the  law  does  not  make  men  good 
simply,  but  in  respect  to  that  particular  government.  In 
this  way  good  is  found  even  in  things  that  are  bad  of  them- 
selves :  thus  a  man  is  called  a  good  robber,  because  he  works 
in  a  way  that  is  adapted  to  his  end. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Virtue  is  twofold,  as  explained  above 
(Q.  LXIIL,  A.  2),  viz.,  acquired  and  infused.  Now  the 
fact  of  being  accustomed  to  an  action  contributes  to  both, 
but  in  different  ways;  for  it  causes  the  acquired  virtue; 
while  it  disposes  to  infused  virtue,  and  preserves  and  fosters 
it  when  it  already  exists.  And  since  law  is  given  for  the 
purpose  of  directing  human  acts ;  as  far  as  himian  acts  con- 
duce to  virtue,  so  far  does  law  make  men  good.  Wherefore 
the  Philosopher  says  in  the  second  book  of  the  Politics 


Q.  92.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  24 

{Ethic,  ii.)  that  lawgivers  make  men  good  by  habituating  them 
to  good  works. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  is  not  always  through  perfect  goodness 
of  virtue  that  one  obeys  the  law,  but  sometimes  it  is  through 
fear  of  punishment,  and  sometimes  from  the  mere  dictate 
of  reason,  which  is  a  beginning  of  virtue,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  LXIIL,  A.  I). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  goodness  of  any  part  is  considered  in 
comparison  with  the  whole ;  hence  Augustine  says  {Conf.  iii.) 
that  unseemly  is  the  part  that  harmonizes  not  with  the  whole. 
Since  then  every  man  is  a  part  of  the  state,  it  is  impossible 
that  a  man  be  good,  unless  he  be  well  proportionate  to  the 
common  good:  nor  can  the  whole  be  well  consistent  unless 
its  parts  be  proportionate  to  it.  Consequently  the  common 
good  of  the  state  cannot  flourish,  unless  the  citizens  be 
virtuous,  at  least  those  whose  business  it  is  to  govern.  But 
it  is  enough  for  the  good  of  the  community,  that  the  other 
citizens  be  so  far  virtuous  that  they  obey  the  commands  of 
their  rulers.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  [Polit.  iii.)  that 
the  virtue  of  a  sovereign  is  the  same  as  that  of  a  good  man,  but 
the  virtue  of  any  common  citizen  is  not  the  same  as  that  of  a 
good  man. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  A  tyrannical  law,  through  not  being  accord- 
ing to  reason,  is  not  a  law,  absolutely  speaking,  but  rather  a 
perversion  of  law ;  and  yet  in  so  far  as  it  is  something  in  the 
nature  of  a  law,  it  aims  at  the  citizens  being  good.  For  all 
it  has  in  the  nature  of  a  law  consists  in  its  being  an  ordinance 
made  by  a  superior  to  his  subjects,  and  aims  at  being  obeyed 
by  them,  which  is  to  make  them  good,  not  simply,  but  with 
respect  to  that  particular  government. 

Second  Article, 
whether  the  acts  of  law  are  suitably  assigned  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  acts  of  law  are  not  suitably 
assigned  as  consisting  in  command,  prohibition,  permission 
and  punishment.     For  every  law  is  a  general  precept,  as  the 


25  THE  EFFECTS  OF  LAW         Q.  92.  Art.  2 

jurist  states  (ibid.).  But  command  and  precept  are  the 
same.     Therefore  the  other  three  are  superfluous. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  effect  of  a  law  is  to  induce  its  subjects 
to  be  good,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  But  counsel  aims  at  a 
higher  good  than  a  command  does.  Therefore  it  belongs 
to  law  to  counsel  rather  than  to  command. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  just  as  punishment  stirs  a  man  to 
good  deeds,  so  does  reward.  Therefore  if  to  punish  is 
reckoned  an  effect  of  law,  so  also  is  to  reward. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  the  intention  of  a  lawgiver  is  to  make 
men  good,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  But  he  that  obeys  the 
law,  merely  through  fear  of  being  punished,  is  not  good: 
because  although  a  good  deed  may  be  done  through  servile 
fear,  i.e.,  fear  of  punishment,  it  is  not  done  well,  as  Augustine 
says  [Contra  duas  Epist.  Pelag.  ii.).  Therefore  punishment 
is  not  a  proper  effect  of  law. 

On  the  contrary,  Isidore  says  [Etym.  v.) :  Every  law  either 
permits  something,  as  :  'A  brave  man  may  demand  his 
reward  '  .•  or  forbids  something,  as :  *  No  man  may  ask  a 
consecrated  virgin  in  marriage  '  .*  or  punishes,  as :  *  Let  him 
that  commits  a  murder  be  put  to  death. "^ 

I  answer  that.  Just  as  an  assertion  is  a  dictate  of  reason 
asserting  something,  so  is  a  law  a  dictate  of  reason,  com- 
manding something.  Now  it  is  proper  to  reason  to  lead 
from  one  thing  to  another.  Wherefore  just  as,  in  demon- 
strative sciences,  the  reason  leads  us  from  certain  principles 
to  assent  to  the  conclusion,  so  it  induces  us  by  some  means 
to  assent  to  the  precept  of  the  law. 

Now  the  precepts  of  law  are  concerned  with  human  acts, 
in  which  the  law  directs,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  AA.  i,  2; 
Q.  XCL,  A.  4).  Again,  there  are  three  kinds  of  human 
acts:  for,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XVIIL,  A.  8),  some  acts  are 
good  genericaDy,  viz.,  acts  of  virtue;  and  in  respect  of  these 
the  act  of  the  law  is  a  precept  or  command,  for  the  law 
commands  all  acts  of  virtue  [Ethic,  v.).  Some  acts  are  evil 
generically,  viz.,  acts  of  vice,  and  in  respect  of  these  the  law 
forbids.  Some  acts  are  generically  indifferent,  and  in 
respect  of  these  the  law  permits ;  and  all  acts  that  are  either 


Q.  92.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  26 

not  distinctly  good  or  not  distinctly  bad  may  be  called 
indifferent. — And  it  is  the  fear  of  punishment  that  law  makes 
use  of  in  order  to  ensure  obedience:  in  which  respect 
punishment  is  an  effect  of  law. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Just  as  to  cease  from  evil  is  a  kind  of  good, 
so  a  prohibition  is  a  kind  of  precept:  and  accordingly,  taking 
precept  in  a  wide  sense,  every  law  is  a  kind  of  precept. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  To  advise  is  not  a  proper  act  of  law,  but 
may  be  within  the  competency  even  of  a  private  person, 
who  cannot  make  a  law.  Wherefore  too  the  Apostle,  after 
giving  a  certain  counsel  (i  Cor.  vii.  12)  says:  /  speak,  not  the 
Lord.  Consequently  it  is  not  reckoned  as  an  effect  of 
law. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  To  reward  may  also  pertain  to  anyone :  but 
to  punish  pertains  to  none  but  the  framer  of  the  law,  by 
whose  authority  the  pain  is  inflicted.  Wherefore  to  reward 
is  not  reckoned  an  effect  of  law,  but  only  to  punish. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  From  becoming  accustomed  to  avoid  evil 
and  fulfil  what  is  good,  through  fear  of  punishment,  one  is 
sometimes  led  on  to  do  so  likewise,  with  delight  and  of  one's 
own  accord.  Accordingly,  law,  even  by  punishing,  leads 
men  on  to  being  good. 


QUESTION  XCIII. 

OF  THE  ETERNAL  LAW. 

(7w  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  each  law  by  itself;  and  (i)  The 
eternal  law:  (2)  The  natural  law:  (3)  The  human  law :  (4)  The 
old  law:  (5)  The  new  law,  which  is  the  law  of  the  Gospel. 
Of  the  sixth  law  which  is  the  law  of  the  '  fomes,'  sufhce  what 
we  have  said  when  treating  of  original  sin. 

Concerning  the  first  there  are  six  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  What  is  the  eternal  law  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  known 
to  all  ?  (3)  Whether  every  law  is  derived  from  it  ? 
(4)  Whether  necessary  things  are  subject  to  the  eternal 
law  ?  (5)  Whether  natural  contingencies  are  subject  to  the 
eternal  law  ?  (6)  Whether  all  human  things  are  subject 
to  it  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  the  eternal  law  is  a  sovereign  type* 
existing  in  god  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  eternal  law  is  not  a  sover- 
eign type  existing  in  God.  For  there  is  only  one  eternal 
law.  But  there  are  many  types  of  things  in  the  Divine 
mind;  for  Augustine  says  [Qq.  83)  that  God  made  each  thing 
according  to  its  type.  Therefore  the  eternal  law  does  not 
seem  to  be  a  type  existing  in  the  Divine  mind. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  it  is  essential  to  a  law  that  it  be  pro- 
mulgated by  word,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  4).  But 
Word  is  a  Personal  name  in  God,  as  stated  in  the  First 

*  Ratio. 
27 


Q.  93.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  28 

Part  (Q.  XXXIV.,  A.  i) :  whereas  type  refers  to  the  Essence. 
Therefore  the  eternal  law  is  not  the  same  as  a  Divine  type. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  (De  Vera  Relig.  xxx.) : 
We  see  a  law  above  our  minds,  which  is  called  truth.  But 
the  law  which  is  above  our  minds  is  the  eternal  law.  There- 
fore truth  is  the  eternal  law.  But  the  idea  of  truth  is  not 
the  same  as  the  idea  of  a  type.  Therefore  the  eternal  law 
is  not  the  same  as  the  sovereign  type. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [De  Lib.  Arb.  i.)  that  the 
eternal  law  is  the  sovereign  type,  to  which  we  must  always 
conform. 

I  answer  that,  Just  as  in  every  artificer  there  pre-exists  a 
type  of  the  things  that  are  made  by  his  art,  so  too  in  every 
governor  there  must  pre-exist  the  type  of  the  order  of  those 
things  that  are  to  be  done  by  those  who  are  subject  to  his 
government.  And  just  as  the  type  of  the  things  yet  to  be 
made  by  an  art  is  called  the  art  or  exemplar  of  the  products 
of  that  art,  so  too  the  type  in  him  who  governs  the  acts 
of  his  subjects,  bears  the  character  of  a  law,  provided  the 
other  conditions  be  present  which  we  have  mentioned 
above  (Q.  XC).  Now  God,  by  His  wisdom,  is  the  Creator 
of  all  things,  in  relation  to  which  He  stands  as  the  artificer 
to  the  products  of  his  art,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XIV., 
A.  8).  Moreover  He  governs  all  the  acts  and  movements 
that  are  to  be  found  in  each  single  creature,  as  was  also 
stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  GUI.,  A.  5).  Wherefore  as  the 
type  of  the  Divine  Wisdom,  inasmuch  as  by  It  all  things 
are  created,  has  the  character  of  art,  exemplar  or  idea;  so 
the  type  of  Divine  Wisdom,  as  moving  all  things  to  their 
due  end,  bears  the  character  of  law.  Accordingly  the 
eternal  law  is  nothing  else  than  the  type  of  Divine  Wisdom, 
as  directing  all  actions  and  movements. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Augustine  is  speaking  in  that  passage  of 
the  ideal  types  which  regard  the  proper  nature  of  each  single 
thing ;  and  consequently  in  them  there  is  a  certain  distinction 
and  plurality,  according  to  their  different  relations  to 
things,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XV.,  A.  2).  But  law 
is  said  to  direct  human  acts  by  ordaining  them  to  the 


29  THE  ETERNAL  LAW  Q.qsArt.  i 

common  good,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2).  And  things, 
wliich  are  in  themselves  different,  may  be  considered  as  one, 
according  as  they  are  ordained  to  one  common  thing.  Where- 
fore the  eternal  law  is  one  since  it  is  the  type  of  this  order. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  With  regard  to  any  sort  of  word,  two  points 
may  be  considered:  viz.,  the  word  itself,  and  that  which  is 
expressed  by  the  word.  For  the  spoken  word  is  something 
uttered  by  the  mouth  of  man,  and  expresses  that  which  is 
signified  by  the  human  word.  The  same  applies  to  the 
human  mental  word,  which  is  nothing  else  than  something 
conceived  by  the  mind,  by  which  man  expresses  his  thoughts 
mentally.  So  then  in  God  the  Word  conceived  by  the 
intellect  of  the  Father  is  the  name  of  a  Person:  but  all 
things  that  are  in  the  Father's  knowledge,  whether  they 
refer  to  the  Essence  or  to  the  Persons,  or  to  the  works  of 
God,  are  expressed  by  this  Word,  as  Augustine  declares 
(De  Trin.  xv.).  And  among  other  things  expressed  by  this 
Word,  the  eternal  law  itself  is  expressed  thereby.  Nor  does 
it  follow  that  the  eternal  law  is  a  Personal  name  in  God: 
yet  it  is  appropriated  to  the  Son,  on  account  of  the  kinship 
between  type  and  word. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  types  of  the  Divine  intellect  do  not 
stand  in  the  same  relation  to  things,  as  the  types  of  the 
human  intellect.  For  the  human  intellect  is  measured  by 
things,  so  that  a  human  concept  is  not  true  by  reason  of 
itself,  but  by  reason  of  its  being  consonant  with  things,  since 
an  opinion  is  tnte  or  false  according  as  it  answers  to  the  reality. 
But  the  Divine  intellect  is  the  measure  of  things :  since  each 
thing  has  so  far  truth  in  it,  as  it  represents  the  Divine  intellect, 
as  was  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XVL,  A.  i).  Consequently 
the  Divine  intellect  is  true  in  itself ;  and  its  type  is  truth  itself. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  eternal  law  is  known  to  all  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  eternal  law  is  not  known 
to  all.     Because,  as  the  Apostle  says   (i  Cor.  ii.   11),  the 


Q.  9j.  Ari.  2     TH E  "  SUiMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  30 

tilings  tliat  arc  of  (rod  no  nuui  hnowcth,  but  the  Spirit  of  God. 
\^\xi  the  eternal  law  is  a  type  existing  in  the  Divine  mind. 
Therefore  it  is  unknown  to  all  save  God  alone. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  as  Augustine  says  {Dc  Lib.  Arb.  i.)  the 
eternal  law  is  that  by  which  it  is  right  that  all  things  should 
be  most  orderly.  But  all  do  not  know  how  all  things 
are  most  orderly.  Therefore  all  do  not  know  the  eternal 
law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  [De  Vera  Relig.  xxxi.) 
that  the  eternal  law  is  not  subject  to  the  judgment  of  man. 
But  according  to  Ethic,  i.  any  man  can  judge  well  of  what  he 
knows.     Therefore  the  eternal  law  is  not  known  to  us. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [De  Lib.  Arb.  i.)  that 
knowledge  of  the  eternal  law  is  imprinted  on  us. 

I  answer  that,  A  thing  may  be  known  in  two  ways:  first, 
in  itself;  secondly,  in  its  effect,  wherein  some  likeness  of 
that  thing  is  found:  thus  someone  not  seeing  the  sun  in  its 
substance,  may  know  it  by  its  rays.  So  then  no  one  can 
know  the  eternal  law,  as  it  is  in  itself,  except  the  blessed 
who  see  God  in  His  Essence.  But  e^^er^ratiQual  creature 
knows  it  in  its  reflection,  greater  or  less.  For  every  know- 
ledge of  truth  is  a  kind  of  reflection  and  participation  of  the 
eternal  law,  which  is  the  unchangeable  truth,  as  Augustine 
says  [De  Vera  Relig.  xxxi.).  Now  all  men  know  the  truth 
to  a  certain  extent,  at  least  as  to  the  common  principles  of 
the  natural  law:  and  as  to  the  others,  they  partake  of  the 
knowledge  of  truth,  some  more,  some  less;  and  in  this 
respect  are  more  or  less  cognisant  of  the  eternal  law. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  We  cannot  know  the  things  that  are  of  God, 
as  they  are  in  themselves;  but  they  are  made  known  to  us 
in  their  effects,  according  to  Rom.  i.  20:  The  invisible  things 
of  God  .  .  .  are  clearly  seen,  being  understood  by  the  things  that 
are  made. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Although  each  one  know^s  the  eternal  law 
according  to  his  own  capacity,  in  the  way  explained  above, 
yet  none  can  comprehend  it:  for  it  cannot  be  made  per- 
fectly known  by  its  effects.  Therefore  it  does  not  follow 
that  anyone  who  knows  the  eternal  law  in  the  way  afore- 


31  THE  ETERNAL  LAW  Q.  93.  Art.  3 

said,  knows  also  the  whole  order  of  things,  whereby  they  are 
most  orderly. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  To  judge  of  a  thing  may  be  understood  in 
two  ways.  First,  as  when  a  cognitive  power  judges  of  its 
proper  object,  according  to  Job.  xii.  11 :  Doth  not  the  car 
discern  words,  and  the  palate  of  him  that  eatcth,  the  taste  ? 
It  is  to  this  kind  of  judgment  that  the  Philosopher  alludes 
when  he  says  that  anyone  can  judge  well  of  what  he  knows, 
by  judging,  namely,  whether  what  is  put  forward  is  true. 
In  another  way  we  speak  of  a  superior  judging  of  a  sub- 
ordinate by  a  kind  of  practical  judgment,  as  to  whether  he 
should  be  such  and  such  or  not.  And  thus  none  can  judge 
of  the  eternal  law. 

^  Third  Article, 
whether  every  law  is  derived  from  the  eternal  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  not  every  law  is  derived  from 
the  eternal  law.  For  there  is  a  law  of  the  '  fomes,'  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XCI.,  A.  6),  which  is  not  derived  from  that  Divine 
law  which  is  the  eternal  law,  since  thereunto  pertains  the 
prudence  of  the  flesh,  of  which  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  viii.  7) 
that  it  cannot  be  subject  to  the  law  of  God.  Therefore  not 
every  law  is  derived  from  the  eternal  law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  nothing  unjust  can  be  derived  from  the 
eternal  law,  because,  as  stated  above  (A.  2,  Obj.  2),  the 
eternal  law  is  that,  according  to  which  it  is  right  that  all  things 
should  be  most  orderly.  But  some  laws  are  unjust,  according 
to  Isa.  X.  I :  Woe  to  them  that  make  wicked  laws.  Therefore 
not  every  law  is  derived  from  the  eternal  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  [De  Lib.  Arb.  i.)  that  the 
law  which  is  framed  for  ruling  the  people,  rightly  permits 
many  things  which  are  punished  by  Divine  providence.  But 
the  type  of  Divine  providence  is  the  eternal  law,  as  stated 
above  (A.  i) .  Therefore  not  even  every  good  law  is  derived 
from  the  eternal  law. 

On  the  contrary.  Divine  Wisdom  says  (Pro v.  viii.  15) : 
By  Me  kings  reign,  and  lawgivers  decree  just  things.     But 


Q.  93.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  32 

the  type  of  Divine  Wisdom  is  the  eternal  law,  as  stated 
above  (A.  i).  Therefore  all  laws  proceed  from  the  eternal 
law. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  AA.  i,  2),  law 
denotes  a  kind  of  plan  directing  acts  towards  an  end.  Now 
wherever  there  are  movers  ordained  to  one  another,  the 
power  of  the  second  mover  must  needs  be  derived  from  the 
power  of  the  first  mover;  since  the  second  mover  does  not 
move  except  in  so  far  as  it  is  moved  by  the  first.  Wherefore 
we  observe  the  same  in  all  those  who  govern,  so  that  the 
plan  of  government  is  derived  by  secondary  governors 
from  the  governor  in  chief:  thus  the  plan  of  what  is  to  be 
done  in  a  state  flows  from  the  king's  command  to  his  inferior 
administrators :  and  again  in  things  of  art  the  plan  of  what- 
ever is  to  be  done  by  art  flows  from  the  chief  craftsman  to 
the  under- craftsmen  who  work  with  their  hands.  Since 
then  the  eternal  law  is  the  plan  of  government  in  the  Chief 
Governor,  all  the  plans  of  government  in  the  inferior 
governors  must  be  derived  from  the  eternal  law.  But 
these  plans  of  inferior  governors  are  all  other  laws  besides 
the  eternal  law.  Therefore  all  laws,  in  so  far  as  they  partake 
of  mghpreason,  are  derived  from  the  eternal  law.  Hence 
Augustine  says  [De  Lib.  Arb.  i.)  that  in  temporal  law  there  is 
nothing  just  and  lawful,  but  what  man  has  drawn  from  the 
eternal  law. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  '  fomes'  has  the  nature  of  law  in  man, 
in  so  far  as  it  is  a  punishment  resulting  from  Divine  justice; 
and  in  this  respect  it  is  evident  that  it  is  derived  from  the 
eternal  law.  But  in  so  far  as  it  denotes  a  proneness  to  sin, 
it  is  contrary  to  the  Divine  law,  and  has  not  the  nature  of 
law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCL,  A.  6). 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Human  law  has  the  nature  of  law  in  so  far 
as  it  partakes  of  right  reason;  and  it  is  clear  that,  in  this 
respect,  it  is  derived  from  the  eternal  law.  But  in  so  far  as 
it  deviates  from  reason,  it  is  called  an  imjust  law,  and  has 
the  nature,  not  of  law  but  of  violence.  Nevertheless  even 
an  unjust  law,  in  so  far  as  it  retains  some  appearance  of  law, 
though   being   framed  by  one  who  is  in  power,  is  deprived 


33  THE  ETERNAL  LAW  Q.  93.  Art.  4 

from  the  eternal  law;  since  all  power  is  from  the  Lord  God, 
according  to  Rom.  xiii.  i. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Human  law  is  said  to  permit  certain  things, 
not  as  approving  of  them,  but  as  being  unable  to  direct  them. 
And  many  things  are  directed  by  the  Divine  law,  which 
human  law  is  unable  to  direct,  because  more  things  are 
subject  to  a  higher  than  to  a  lower  cause.  Hence  the  very 
fact  that  human  law  does  not  meddle  with  matters  it  cannot 
direct,  comes  under  the  ordination  of  the  eternal  law.  It 
would  be  different,  were  human  law  to  sanction  what  the 
eternal  law  condemns.  Consequently  it  does  not  follow 
that  human  law  is  not  derived  from  the  eternal  law,  but  that 
it  is  not  on  a  perfect  equality  with  it. 


Fourth  Article. 


^^ 


WHETHER    NECESSARY    AND    ETERNAL    THINGS    ARE    SUBJECT 
TO   THE   ETERNAL   LAW  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  necessary  and  eternal  things 
are  subject  to  the  eternal  law.  For  whatever  is  reasonable 
is  subject  to  reason.  But  the  Divine  will  is  reasonable,  for 
it  is  just.  Therefore  it  is  subject  to  (the  Divine)  reason. 
But  the  eternal  law  is  the  Divine  reason.  Therefore  God's 
will  is  subject  to  the  eternal  law.  But  God's  will  is  eternal. 
Therefore  eternal  and  necessary  things  are  subject  to  the 
eternal  law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  whatever  is  subject  to  the  King,  is  subject 
to  the  King's  law.  Now  the  Son,  according  to  i  Cor.  xv. 
28,  24,  shall  be  subject  .  .  .  to  God  and  the  Father,  .  .  .  when 
He  shall  have  delivered  up  the  Kingdom  to  Him.  Therefore 
the  Son,  Who  is  eternal,  is  subject  to  the  eternal  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  eternal  law  is  Divine  providence 
as  a  type.  But  many  necessary  things  are  subject  to 
Divine  providence:  for  instance,  the  stability  of  incorporeal 
substances  and  of  the  heavenly  bodies.  Therefore  even 
necessary  things  are  subject  to  the  eternal  law. 

On  the  contrary,  Things  that  are  necessary  cannot  be 

II-  3  3 


O.  03.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  34 

otherwise,  and  consequently  need  no  restraining.  But  laws 
are  imposed  on  men,  in  order  to  restrain  them  from  evil,  as 
explained  above  (Q.  XCIL,  A.  2).  Therefore  necessary 
things  arc  not  subject  to  the  eternal  law. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  the  eternal  law  is 
the  type  of  the  Divine  government.  Consequently  what- 
ever is  subject  to  the  Divine  government,  is  subject  to  the 
eternal  law:  while  if  anything  is  not  subject  to  the  Divine 
government,  neither  is  it  subject  to  the  eternal  law.  The 
application  of  this  distinction  may  be  gathered  by  looking 
around  us.  For  those  things  are  subject  to  human  govern- 
ment, which  can  be  done  by  man;  but  what  pertains  to  the 
nature  of  man  is  not  subject  to  human  government;  for 
instance,  that  he  should  have  a  soul,  hands,  or  feet.  Ac- 
cordingly all  that  is  in  things  created  by  God,  whether  it  be 
contingent  or  necessary,  is  subject  to  the  eternal  law:  while 
things  pertaining  to  the  Divine  Nature  or  Essence  are  not 
subject  to  the  eternal  law,  but  are  the  eternal  law  itself. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  We  may  speak  of  God's  will  in  two  ways. 
First,  as  to  the  will  itself :  and  thus,  since  God's  will  is  His 
very  Essence,  it  is  subject  neither  to  the  Divine  government, 
nor  to  the  eternal  law,  but  is  the  same  thing  as  the  eternal 
law.  Secondly,  we  may  speak  of  God's  will,  as  to  the 
things  themselves  that  God  wills  about  creatures;  which 
things  are  subject  to  the  eternal  law,  in  so  far  as  they  are 
planned  by  Divine  Wisdom.  In  reference  to  these  things 
God's  will  is  said  to  be  reasonable  (rationalis) :  though  re- 
garded in  itself  it  should  rather  be  called  their  type  (ratio) . 

Reply  Obj.  2.  God  the  Son  was  not  made  by  God,  but 
was  naturally  born  of  God.  Consequently  He  is  not  subject 
to  Divine  providence  or  to  the  eternal  law:  but  rather  is 
Himself  the  eternal  law  by  a  kind  of  appropriation,  as 
Augustine  explains  (De  Vera  Relig.  xxxi.).  But  He  is  said 
to  be  subject  to  the  Father  by  reason  of  His  human  nature, 
in  respect  of  which  also  the  Father  is  said  to  be  greater 
than  He. 

The  third  objection  we  grant,  because  it  deals  with  those 
necessary  things  that  are  created. 


35  THE  ETERNAL  LAW  Q.  93.  Art.  5 

Reply  Obj.  4.  As  the  Philosopher  says  [Mctaph.  v.),  some 
necessary  things  have  a  cause  of  their  necessity:  and  thus 
they  derive  from  something  else  the  fact  that  they  cannot 
be  otherwise.  And  this  is  in  itself  a  most  effective  restraint ; 
for  whatever  is  restrained,  is  said  to  be  restrained  in  so  far 
as  it  cannot  do  otherwise  than  it  is  allowed  to. 


Fifth  Article. 

whether  natural  contingents  are  subject  to  the 

eternal  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  natural  contingents  are  not 
subject  to  the  eternal  law.  Because  promulgation  is  essen- 
tial to  law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  4).  But  a  law 
cannot  be  promulgated  except  to  rational  creatures,  to 
whom  it  is  possible  to  make  an  announcement.  Therefore 
none  but  rational  creatures  are  subject  to  the  eternal  law; 
and  consequently  natural  contingents  are  not. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Whatever  obeys  reason  partakes  somewhat 
of  reason,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  i.  But  the  eternal  law  is  the 
supreme  type,  as  stated  above  (A.  i.)  Since  then  natural 
contingents  do  not  partake  of  reason  in  any  way,  but  are 
altogether  void  of  reason,  it  seems  that  they  are  not  subject 
to  the  eternal  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  eternal  law  is  most  efhcient.  But 
in  natural  contingents  defects  occur.  Therefore  they  are 
not  subject  to  the  eternal  law. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Prov.  viii.  29) :  When  He 
compassed  the  sea  with  its  bounds,  and  set  a  law  to  the  waters, 
that  they  should  not  pass  their  limits. 

I  answer  that.  We  must  speak  otherwise  of  the  law  of 
man,  than  of  the  eternal  law  which  is  the  law  of  God.  For 
the  law  of  man  extends  only  to  rational  creatures  subject 
to  man.  The  reason  of  this  is  because  law  directs  the 
actions  of  those  that  are  subject  to  the  government  of 
someone;  wherefore,  properly  speaking,  none  imposes  a 
law  on  his  own  actions.     Now  whatever  is  done  regarding 


Q.  93.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  36 

the  use  of  irrational  things  subject  to  man,  is  done  by  the 
act  of  man  himself  moving  those  things,  for  these  irrational 
creatures  do  not  move  themselves,  but  are  moved  by  others, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  2).  Consequently  man  cannot 
impose  laws  on  irrational  beings,  however  much  they  may 
be  subject  to  him.  But  he  can  impose  laws  on  rational 
beings  subject  to  him,  in  so  far  as  by  his  command  or  pro- 
nouncement of  any  kind,  he  imprints  on  their  minds  a  rule 
which  is  a  principle  of  action. 

Now  just  as  man,  by  such  pronouncement,  impresses  a 
kind  of  inward  principle  of  action  on  the  man  that  is  subject 
to  him,  so  God  imprints  on  the  whole  of  nature  the  principles 
of  its  proper  actions.  And  so,  in  this  way,  God  is  said  to 
command  the  whole  of  nature,  according  to  Ps.  cxlviii.  6: 
He  hath  made  a  decree,  and  it  shall  not  pass  away.  And  thus 
all  actions  and  movements  of  the  whole  of  nature  are  subject 

^r-i'.r-  -        -        I     -  i.i,  I,  •* 

to  the  eternal  law.  ConsequentlyQrrational^creatures  are 
subject  to  the  eternal  law,  through  being  moved  by  Divine 
providence;  but  not,  as  (mtional  creatures  are,  through 
understanding  the  Divine  commandment. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  impression  of  an  inward  active  principle 
is  to  natural  things,  what  the  promulgation  of  law  is  to 
men :  because  law,  by  being  promulgated,  imprints  on  man 
a  directive  principle  of  human  actions,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Irrational  creatures  neither  partake  of  nor 
are  obedient  to  human  reason:  whereas  they  do  partake  of 
the  Divine  Reason  by  obeying  it;  because  the  power  of 
Divine  Reason  extends  over  more  things  than  human  reason 
does.  And  as  the  members  of  the  human  body  are  moved 
at  the  command  of  reason,  and  yet  do  not  partake  of 
reason,  since  they  have  no  apprehension  subordinate  to 
reason;  so  too  irrational  creatures  are  moved  by  God, 
without,  on  that  account,  being  rational. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  the  defects  which  occur  in  natural 
things  are  outside  the  order  of  particular  causes,  they  are 
not  outside  the  order  of  universal  causes,  especially  of  the 
First  Cause,  i.e.,  God,  from  Whose  providence  nothing  can 
escape,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XXII.,  A.  2).     And 


37  THE  ETERNAL  LAW  g.  93.  Art.  6 

since  the  eternal  law  is  the  type  of  Divine  providence,  as 
stated  above  (A.  i),  hence  the  defects  of  natural  things  are 
subject  to  the  eternal  law. 


Sixth  Article. 

whether  all  human  affairs  are  subject  to  the 

eternal  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  not  all  human  affairs  are 
subject  to  the  eternal  law.  For  the  Apostle  says  (Gal.  v.  18) : 
//  you  are  led  by  the  spirit  you  are  not  under  the  law.  But 
the  righteous  who  are  the  sons  of  God  by  adoption,  are  led 
by  the  spirit  of  God,  according  to  Rom.  viii.  14:  Whosoever 
are  led  by  the  Spirit  of  God ,  they  are  the  sons  of  God.  Therefore 
not  all  men  are  under  the  eternal  law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  viii.  7) :  The 
prudence  (Vulg.,  wisdom)  of  the  flesh  is  an  enemy  to  God  :  for 
it  is  not  subject  to  the  law  of  God.  But  many  are  those  in 
whom  the  prudence  of  the  flesh  dominates.  Therefore  all 
men  are  not  subject  to  the  eternal  law  which  is  the  law 
of  God. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  [De  Lib.  Arb.  i.)  that  the 
eternal  law  is  that  by  which  the  wicked  deserve  misery,  the  good, 
a  life  of  blessedness.  But  those  who  are  already  blessed, 
and  those  who  are  already  lost,  are  not  in  the  state  of  merit. 
Therefore  they  are  not  under  the  eternal  law. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [De  Civ.  Dei,  xix.) :  Nothing 
evades  the  laws  of  the  most  high  Creator  and  Governor,  for  by 
Him  the  peace  of  the  universe  is  administered. 

I  answer  that.  There  are  two  ways  in  which  a  thing  is 
subject  to  the  eternal  law,  as  explained  above  (A.  5) :  first, 
by  partaking  of  the  eternal  law  by  way  of  knowledge; 
secondly,  by  way  of  action  and  passion,  i.e.,  by  partaking 
of  the  eternal  law  by  way  of  an  inward  motive  principle: 
and  in  this  second  way,  irrational  creatures  are  subject  to 
the  eternal  law,  as  stated  above  {ibid.).  But  since  the 
rational  nature,  together  with  that  which  it  has  in  common 


Q.  93.  Art.  6     THE  "  SUMM.A  THEOLOGICA  "  38 

with  all  creatures,  has  something  proper  to  itself  inasmuch  as 
it  is  rational,  consequently  it  is  subject  to  the  eternal  law 
in  both  ways;  because  while  each  rational  creature  has 
some  knowledge  of  the  eternal  law,  as  stated  above  (A.  2), 
it  also  has  a  natural  inclination  to  that  which  is  in  harmony 
with  the  eternal  law;  for  we  are  naturally  adapted  to  he  the 
recipients  of  virtue  [Ethic,  ii.). 

Both  ways,  however,  are  imperfect,  and  to  a  certain  extent 
destroyed,  in  the  wicked;  because  in  them  the  natural 
inclination  to  virtue  is  corrupted  by  vicious  habits,  and, 
moreover,  the  natural  knowledge  of  good  is  darkened  by 
passions  and  habits  of  sin.  But  in  the  good  both  ways  are 
found  more  perfect:  because  in  them,  besides  the  natural 
knowledge  of  good,  there  is  the  added  knowledge  of  faith 
and  wisdom;  and  again,  besides  the  natural  inclination  to 
good,  there  is  the  added  interior  motive  of  grace  and  virtue. 

Accordingly,  the  good  are  perfectly  subject  to  the  eternal 
law,  as  always  acting  according  to  it:  whereas  the  wicked 
are  subject  to  the  eternal  law,  imperfectly  as  to  their  actions, 
indeed,  since  both  their  knowledge  of  good,  and  their  inclina- 
tion thereto,  are  imperfect :  but  this  imperfection  on  the  part 
of  action  is  supplied  on  the  part  of  passion,  in  so  far  as  they 
suffer  what  the  eternal  law  decrees  concerning  them,  accord- 
ing as  they  fail  to  act  in  harmony  with  that  law.  Hence 
Augustine  says  [De  Lib.  Arb.  i.) :  /  esteem  that  the  righteous 
act  according  to  the  eternal  law  ;  and  [De  Catech.  Rud.  xviii.) : 
Out  of  the  just  misery  of  the  souls  which  deserted  Him,  God 
knew  how  to  furnish  the  inferior  parts  of  His  creation  with 
most  suitable  laws. 

Reply  Ohj.  1.  This  saying  of  the  Apostle  may  be  under- 
stood in  two  ways.  First,  so  that  a  man  is  said  to  be  under 
the  law,  through  being  pinned  down  thereby,  against  his 
will,  as  by  a  load.  Hence,  on  the  same  passage  a  gloss  says 
that  he  is  under  the  law,  who  refrains  from  evil  deeds,  through 
fear  of  the  punishment  threatened  by  the  law,  and  not  from 
love  of  virtue.  In  this  way  the  spiritual  man  is  not  under 
the  law,  because  he  fulfils  the  law  willingly,  through  charity 
which  is  poured  into  his  heart  by  the  Holy  Ghost.     Secondly, 


39  THE  ETERNAL  LAW  Q.  93.  Art.  6 

it  can  be  understood  as  meaning  that  the  works  of  a  man, 
who  is  led  by  the  Holy  Ghost,  are  the  works  of  the  Holy 
Ghost  rather  than  his  own.  Therefore,  since  the  Holy 
Ghost  is  not  under  the  law,  as  neither  is  the  Son,  as  stated 
above  (A.  4  ad  2) ;  it  follows  that  such  works,  in  so  far  as 
they  are  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  are  not  under  the  law.  The 
Apostle  witnesses  to  this  when  he  says  (2  Cor.  iii.  17) :  Where 
the  Spirit  of  the  Lord  is,  there  is  liberty. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  prudence  of  the  flesh  cannot  be  subject 
to  the  law  of  God  as  regards  action;  since  it  inclines  to 
actions  contrary  to  the  Divine  law:  yet  it  is  subject  to  the 
law  of  God,  as  regards  passion;  since  it  deserves  to  suffer 
punishment  according  to  the  law  of  Divine  justice.  Never- 
theless in  no  man  does  the  prudence  of  the  flesh  dominate 
so  far  as  to  destroy  the  whole  good  of  his  nature:  and  con- 
sequently there  remains  in  man  the  inclination  to  act  in 
accordance  with  the  eternal  law.  For  we  have  seen  above 
(Q.  LXXXV.,  A.  2)  that  sin  does  not  destroy  entirely  the 
good  of  nature. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  A  thing  is  maintained  in  the  end  and  moved 
towards  the  end  by  one  and  the  same  cause:  thus  gravity 
which  makes  a  heavy  body  rest  in  the  lower  place  is  also 
the  cause  of  its  being  moved  thither.  We  therefore  reply 
that  as  it  is  according  to  the  eternal  law  that  some  deserve 
happiness,  others  unhappiness,  so  is  it  by  the  eternal  law 
that  some  are  maintained  in  a  happy  state,  others  in  an 
unhappy  state.  Accordingly  both  the  blessed  and  the 
damned  are  under  the  eternal  law. 


QUESTION  XCIV. 

OF  THE  NATURAL  LAW. 

{In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  natural  law;  concerning  which 
there  are  six  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  What  is  the  natural 
law  ?  (2)  What  are  the  precepts  of  the  natural  law  ? 
(3)  Whether  all  acts  of  virtue  are  prescribed  by  the  natural 
law  ?  (4)  Whether  the  natural  law  is  the  same  in  all  ? 
(5)  Whether  it  is  changeable  ?  (6)  Whether  it  can  be 
abolished  from  the  heart  of  man  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  the  natural  law  is  a  habit  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  natural  law  is  a  habit. 
Because,  as  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  ii.),  there  are  three 
things  in  the  soul,  power,  habit  and  passion.  But  the  natural 
law  is  not  one  of  the  soul's  powers :  nor  is  it  one  of  the 
passions;  as  we  may  see  by  going  through  them  one  by 
one.     Therefore  the  natural  law  is  a  habit. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Basil  (Damascene,  De  Fide  Orthod.  iv.) 
says  that  the  conscience  or  synderesis  is  the  law  of  our  mind  ; 
which  can  only  apply  to  the  natural  law.  But  the  synderesis 
is  a  habit,  as  was  shown  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  LXXIX., 
A.  12).     Therefore  the  natural  law  is  a  habit. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  natural  law  abides  in  man  always,  as 
will  be  shown  further  on  (A.  6)'.  But  man's  reason,  which 
the  law  regards,  does  not  always  think  about  the  natural 
law.     Therefore  the  natural  law  is  not  an  act,  but  a  habit. 

40 


41  THE  NATURAL  LAW  Q.  94  Art.  1 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Bono  Conjug.  xxi.) 
that  a  habit  is  thai  whereby  something  is  done  when  necessary. 
But  such  is  not  the  natural  law:  since  it  is  in  infants  and 
in  the  damned  who  cannot  act  by  it.  Therefore  the  natural 
law  is  not  a  habit. 

/  answer  that,  A  thing  may  be  called  a  habit  in  two  ways. 
First,  properly  and  essentially:  and  thus  the  natural  law  is 
not  a  habit.  For  it  has  been  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  i 
ad  2)  that  the  natural  law  is  something  appointed  by  reason, 
just  as  a  proposition  is  a  work  of  reason.  Now  that  which 
a  man  does  is  not  the  same  as  that  whereby  he  does  it :  for 
he  makes  a  becoming  speech  by  the  habit  of  grammar. 
Since  then  a  habit  is  that  by  which^we  acjL. a  law  cannot 
be  a  habit  groperly  and  essentially. 

Secondly,  Ihe  term  habit  may  be  applied  to  that  which 
we  hold  by  a  habit :  thus  faith  may  mean  that  which  we  hold 
by  faith.  And  accordingly,  since  the  precepts  of  the  natural 
law  are  sometimes  considered  by  reason  actually,  w^hile 
sometimes  they  are  in  the  reason  only  habitually,  in  this 
way  the  natural  law  may  be  called  a  habit.  Thus,  in  specu- 
lative matters,  the  indemonstrable  principles  are  not  the 
habit  itself  whereby  we  hold  those  principles,  but  are  the 
principles  the  habit  of  which  we  possess. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  Philosopher  proposes  there  to  discover 
the  genus  of  virtue;  and  since  it  is  evident  that  virtue  is  a 
principle  of  action,  he  mentions  only  those  things  which  are 
principles  of  human  acts,  viz.,  powers,  habits  and  passions. 
But  there  are  other  things  in  the  soul  besides  these  three: 
there  are  acts;  thus  to  will  is  in  the  one  that  wills;  again, 
things  known  are  in  the  knower;  moreover  its  own  natural 
properties  are  in  the  soul,  such  as  immortality  and  the  like. 
Reply  Obj.  2.  Synderesis  is  said  to  be  the  law  of  our  mind, 
because  it  is  a  habit  containing  the  precepts  of  the  natural 
law,  which  are  the  first  principles  of  human  actions. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  This  argument  proves  that  the  natural  law 
is  held  habitually :  and  this  is  granted. 

To  the  argument  advanced  in  the  contrary  sense  we  reply 
that  sometimes  a  man  is  unable  to  make  use  of  that  which 


Q.  94.  Art.  z       THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  42 

is  in  him  habitually,  on  account  of  some  impediment:  thus, 
on  account  of  sleep,  a  man  is  unable  to  use  the  habit  of 
science.  In  like  manner,  through  the  deficiency  of  his  age, 
a  child  cannot  use  the  habit  of  understanding  of  principles, 
or  the  natural  law,  which  is  in  him  habitually. 


Second  Article. 

whether  the  natural  law  contains  several  precepts, 

or  one  only  ? 

'  we  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  natural  law  contains,  not 
several  precepts,  but  one  only.  For  law  is  a  kind  of  precept, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XCII.,  A.  2).  If  therefore  there  were 
many  precepts  of  the  natural  law,  it  would  follow  that 
there  are  also  many  natural  laws. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  natural  law  is  consequent  to  human 
nature.  But  human  nature,  as  a  whole,  is  one;  though,  as 
to  its  parts,  it  is  manifold.  Therefore,  either  there  is  but 
one  precept  of  the  law  of  nature,  on  account  of  the  unity 
of  nature  as  a  whole ;  or  there  are  many,  by  reason  of  the 
number  of  parts  of  human  nature.  The  result  would  be 
that  even  things  relating  to  the  inclination  of  the  con- 
cupiscible  faculty  belong  to  the  natural  law. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  law  is  something  pertaining  to  reason, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  i).  Now  reason  is  but  one  in 
man.     Therefore  there  is  only  one  precept  of  the  natural  law. 

On  the  contrary,  The  precepts  of  the  natural  law  in  man 
stand  in  relation  to  practical  matters,  as  the  first  principles 
to  matters  of  demonstration.  But  there  are  several  first 
indemonstrable  principles.  Therefore  there  are  also  several 
precepts  of  the  natural  law. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XCL,  A.  3),  the  precepts 
of  the  natural  law  are  to  the  practical  reason,  what  the  first 
principles  of  demonstrations  are  to  the  speculative  reason; 
because  both  are  self-evident  principles.  Now  a  thing  is 
said  to  be  self-evident  in  two  ways :  first,  in  itself ;  secondly, 
in  relation  to  us.     Any  proposition  is  said  to  be  self-evident 


43  THE  NATURAL  LAW  0.94.  Art.  2 

in  itself,  if  its  predicate  is  contained  in  the  notion  of  tlie 
subject:  although,  to  one  who  knows  not  the  definition  of 
the  subject,  it  happens  that  such  a  proposition  is  not  self- 
evident.  For  instance,  this  proposition,  Man  is  a  rational 
being,  is,  in  its  very  nature,  self-evident,  since  who  says 
man,  says  a  rational  being  :  and  yet  to  one  who  knows  not 
what  a  man  is,  this  proposition  is  not  self-evident.  Hence 
it  is  that,  as  Boethius  says  (Dc  Hebdom.),  certain  axioms 
or  propositions  are  universally  self-evident  to  all;  and  such 
are  those  propositions  whose  terms  are  known  to  all,  as, 
Every  whole  is  greater  than  its  part,  and,  Things  equal  to  one 
and  the  same  are  equal  to  one  another.  But  some  propositions 
are  self-evident  only  to  the  wise,  who  understand  the  mean- 
ing of  the  terms  of  such  propositions :  thus  to  one  who  under- 
stands that  an  angel  is  not  a  body,  it  is  self-evident  that  an 
angel  is  not  circumscriptively  in  a  place:  but  this  is  not 
evident  to  the  unlearned,  for  they  cannot  grasp  it. 

Now  a  certain  order  is  to  be  found  in  those  things  that  are 
apprehended  universally.  For  that  which,  before  aught 
else,  falls  under  apprehension,  is  being,  the  notion  of  which 
is  included  in  all  things  whatsoever  a  man  apprehends. 
Wherefore  the  first  indemonstrable  principle  is  that  the  same 
thing  cannot  be  affirmed  and  denied  at  the  same  time,  which  is 
based  on  the  notion  of  being  and  not-being :  and  on  this 
principle  all  others  are  based,  as  is  stated  in  Metaph.  iv. 
Now  as  being  is  the  first  thing  that  falls  under  the  appre- 
hension simply,  so  good  is  the  first  thing  that  falls  under 
the  apprehension  of  the  practical  reason,  which  is  directed 
,  to  action :  since  every  agent  acts  for  an  end  under  the  aspect 
of  good.  Consequently  the  first  principle  in  the  practical 
reason  is  one  founded  on  the  notion  of  good,  viz.,  that  good 
is  that  which  all  things  seek  after.  Hence  tMs  is  the  first_ 
precept  of  law,  that  good  is  to  be  done  and  ensued,  and  evil  is 
to  be  avoided.  All  other  precepts  of  the  natural  law  are  based 
upon  this:  so  that  whatever  the  practical  reason  naturally 
apprehends  as  man's  good  (or  evil)  belongs  to  the  precepts 
of  the  natural  law  as  something  to  be  done  or  avoided.  A  , 

Since,  however,  good  has  the  nature  of  an  end,  and  evil^         ^ 


o.  94.  Art.  z     THI^:  "  SUMMA  THKOLOGICA  "  44 

the  nature  ol  a  contrary,  hence  it  is  that  all  those  things 
to  which  man  has  a  natural  inclination,  are  naturally  appre- 
hended by  reason  as  being  good,  and  consequently  as  objects 
of   pursuit,    and   their   contraries   as  evil,   and  objects   of 
>- avoidance.     Wherefore  according  to  the  order  of  natural 
[  inchnations,  is  the  order  of  the  precepts  of  the  natural  law. 
1    Because  in  man  there  is  first  of  all  an  inclination  to  good 
'    in  accordance  with  the  nature  which  he  has  in  common 
with  all  substances:  inasmuch  as  every  substance  seeks  the 
preservation  of  its  own  being,  according  to  its  nature:  and 
by  reason  of  this  inclination,  whatever  is  a  means  of  pre- 
serving human  life,  and  of  warding  off  its  obstacles,  belongs 
to  the  natural  law.     Secondly,  there  is  in  man  an  inclination 
:   to  things  that  pertain  to  him  more  specially,  according  to 
that  nature  which  he  has  in  common  with  other  animals: 
and  in  virtue  of  this  inclination,  those  things  are  said  to 
belong  to  the  natural  law,  which  nature  has  taught  to  all 
animals  [Pandect.  Just.  I.,  Tit.  I.),  such  as  sexual  intercourse, 
education  of  offspring  and  so  forth.     Thirdly,  there  is  in 
man  an  inclination  to  good,  according  to  the  nature  of  his 
reason,  which  nature  is  proper  to  him:  thus  man  has  a 
natural  inclination  to  know  the  truth  about  God,  and  to 
live  in  society :  and  in  this  respect,  whatever  pertains  to  this 
inclination  belongs  to  the  natural  law;  for  instance,  to  shun 
ignorance,  to  avoid  offending  those  among  whom  one  has  to 
;   live,  and  other  such  things  regarding  the  above  inclination. 
Reply  Ohj.   i.  All  these  precepts   of    the  law  of  nature 
have  the  character  of  one  natural  law,  inasmuch  as  they 
flow  from  one  first  precept. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  AH  the  inclinations  of  any  parts  whatsoever 
of  human  nature,  e.g.,  of  the  concupiscible  and  irascible 
parts,  in  so  far  as  they  are  ruled  by  reason,  belong  to  the 
natural  law,  and  are  reduced  to  one  first  precept,  as  stated 
above :  so  that  the  precepts  of  the  natural  law  are  many  in 
themselves,  but  are  based  on  one  common  foundation. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Although  reason  is  one  in  itself,  yet  it 
directs  all  things  regarding  man;  so  that  whatever  can  be 
ruled  by  reason,  is  contained  under  the  law  of  reason. 


45  THE  NATURAL  LAW  Q.  94.  Art.  3 


Third  Article. 

whether  all  acts  of  virtue  are  prescribed  by  the 

natural  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  not  all  acts  of  virtue  are  pre- 
scribed by  the  natural  law.  Because,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XC,  A.  2)  it  is  essential  to  a  law  that  it  be  ordained  to 
the  common  good.  But  some  acts  of  virtue  are  ordained 
to  the  private  good  of  the  individual,  as  is  evident  especially 
in  regard  to  acts  of  temperance.  Therefore  not  all  acts  of 
virtue  are  the  subject  of  natural  law. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  every  sin  is  opposed  to  some  virtuous 
act.  If  therefore  all  acts  of  virtue  are  prescribed  by  the 
natural  law,  it  seems  to  follow  that  all  sins  are  against 
nature:  whereas  this  applies  to  certain  special  sins. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  those  things  which  are  according  to 
nature  are  common  to  all.  But  acts  of  virtue  are  not 
common  to  all :  since  a  thing  is  virtuous  in  one,  and  vicious 
in  another.  Therefore  not  all  acts  of  virtue  are  prescribed 
by  the  natural  law. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  [De  Fide  Orthod.  iii.)  that 
virtues  are  natural.  Therefore  virtuous  acts  also  are  a  subject 
of  the  natural  law. 

/  answer  that,  We  may  speak  of  virtuous  acts  in  two 
ways:  first,  under  the  aspect  of  virtuous;  secondly,  as  such 
and  such  acts  considered  in  their  proper  species.  If  then 
we  speak  of  acts  of  virtue,  considered  as  virtuous,  thus 
all  virtuous  acts  belong  to  the  natural  law.  For  it  has  been 
stated  (A.  2)  that  to  the  natural  law  belongs  everything 
to  which  a  man  is  inclined  according  to  his  nature.  Now 
each  thing  is  inclined  naturally  to  an  operation  that  is 
suitable  to  it  according  to  its  form:  thus  fire  is  inclined  to 
give  heat.  Wherefore,  since  the  rational  soul  is  the  proper 
form  of  man,  there  is  in  every  man  a  natural  inclination  to 
act  according  to  reason:  and  this  is  to  act  according  to 
virtue.     Consequently,  considered  thus,  all  acts  of  virtue 


Q.  94.  Art.  3     THE  ''  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  46 

are  prescribed  by  the  natural  law:  since  each  one's  reason 
naturally  dictates  to  him  to  act  virtuously.  But  if  we  speak 
of  virtuous  acts,  considered  in  themselves,  i.e.,  in  their 
proper  species,  thus  not  all  virtuous  acts  are  prescribed  by 
the  natural  law:  for  many  things  are  done  virtuously,  to 
which  nature  does  not  incline  at  first;  but  which,  through 
the  inquiry  of  reason,  have  been  found  by  men  to  be  con- 
ducive to  well-living. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Temperance  is  about  the  natural  concu- 
piscences of  food,  drink  and  sexual  matters,  which  are 
indeed  ordained  to  the  natural  common  good,  just  as 
other  matters  of  law  are  ordained  to  the  moral  common 
good. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  By  human  nature  we  may  mean  either  that 
which  is  proper  to  man — and  in  this  sense  all  sins,  as  being 
against  reason,  are  also  against  nature,  as  Damascene 
states  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.) :  or  we  may  mean  that  nature 
which  is  common  to  man  and  other  animals;  and  in  this 
sense,  certain  special  sins  are  said  to  be  against  nature ;  thus 
contrary  to  sexual  intercourse,  which  is  natural  to  all 
animals,  is  unisexual  lust,  which  has  received  the  special 
name  of  the  unnatural  crime. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  This  argument  considers  acts  in  themselves. 
For  it  is  owing  to  the  various  conditions  of  men,  that  certain 
acts  are  virtuous  for  some,  as  being  proportionate  and 
becoming  to  them,  while  they  are  vicious  for  others,  as  being 
out  of  proportion  to  them. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  the  natural  law  is  the  same  in  all  men  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  natural  law  is  not  the  same 
in  all.  For  it  is  stated  in  the  Decretals  [Dist.  i.)  that  the 
natural  law  is  that  which  is  contained  in  the  Law  and  the 
Gospel.  But  this  is  not  common  to  all  men;  because,  as  it  is 
written  (Rom.  x.  16),  all  do  not  obey  the  gospel.  Therefore 
the  natural  law  is  not  the  same  in  all  men. 


47  THE  NATURAL  LAW  Q.  94.  Art.  4 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Things  which  are  according  to  the  law  are 
said  to  be  just,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  v.  But  it  is  stated  in  the 
same  book  that  nothing  is  so  universally  just  as  not  to  be 
subject  to  change  in  regard  to  some  men.  Therefore  even 
the  natural  law  is  not  the  same  in  all  men. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  as  stated  above  (AA.  2,  3),  to  the  natural 
law  belongs  everything  to  which  a  man  is  inclined  according 
to  his  nature.  Now  different  men  are  naturally  inclined 
to  different  things;  some  to  the  desire  of  pleasures,  others 
to  the  desire  of  honours,  and  other  men  to  other  things. 
Therefore  there  is  not  one  natural  law  for  all. 

On  the  contrary,  Isidore  says  [Etym.  v.) :  The  natural  law 
is  common  to  all  nations. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (AA.  2,  3),  to  the  natural 
law  belongs  those  thing's  to  which  a  man  is  inclined  naturally : 
and  among  these  it  is  proper  to  man  to  be  inclined  to  act 
according  to  reason.  Now  the  process  of  reason  is  from  the 
common  to  the  proper,  as  stated  in  Phys.  i.  The  speculative 
reason,  however,  is  differently  situated  in  this  matter,  from 
the  practical  reason.  For,  since  the  speculative  reason  is 
busied  chiefly  with  necessary  things,  which  cannot  be  other- 
wise than  they  are,  its  proper  conclusions,  like  the  universal 
principles,  contain  the  truth  without  fail.  The  practical 
reason,  on  the  other  hand,  is  busied  with  contingent  matters, 
about  which  human  actions  are  concerned :  and  consequently, 
although  there  is  necessity  in  the  general  principles,  the  more 
we  descend  to  matters  of  detail,  the  more  frequently  we 
encounter  defects.  Accordingly  then  in  speculative  matters 
truth  is  the  same  in  all  men,  both  as  to  principles  and  as 
to  conclusions:  although  the  truth  is  not  known  to  all  as 
regards  the  conclusions,  but  only  as  regards  the  principles 
which  are  called  common  notions.  But  in  matters  of  action, 
truth  or  practical  rectitude  is  not  the  same  for  all,  as  to 
matters  of  detail,  but  only  as  to  the  general  principles :  and 
where  there  is  the  same  rectitude  in  matters  of  detail,  it  is 
not  equally  known  to  all. 

It  is  therefore  evident  that,  as  regards  the  general  prin- 
ciples whether  of  speculative  or  of  practical  reason,  truth 


Q.  94.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  48 

or  rectitude  is  the  same  for  all,  and  is  equally  known  by  all. 
As  to  the  proper  conclusions  of  the  speculative  reason,  the 
truth  is  the  same  for  all,  but  is  not  equally  known  to  all: 
thus  it  is  true  for  all  that  the  three  angles  of  a  triangle  are 
together  equal  to  two  right  angles,  although  it  is  not  known 
to  all.  But  as  to  the  proper  conclusions  of  the  practical 
reason,  neither  is  the  truth  or  rectitude  the  same  for  all,  nor, 
where  it  is  the  same,  is  it  equally  known  by  all.  Thus  it  is 
right  and  true  for  all  to  act  according  to  reason:  and  from 
this  principle  it  follows  as  a  proper  conclusion,  that  goods 
entrusted  to  another  should  be  restored  to  their  owner. 
Now  this  is  true  for  the  majority  of  cases :  but  it  may  happen 
in  a  particular  case  that  it  would  be  injurious,  and  therefore 
unreasonable,  to  restore  goods  held  in  trust ;  for  instance  if 
they  are  claimed  for  the  purpose  of  fighting  against  one's 
country.  And  this  principle  will  be  found  to  fail  the  more, 
according  as  we  descend  further  into  detail,  e.g.,  if  one  were 
to  say  that  goods  held  in  trust  should  be  restored  with  such 
and  such  a  guarantee,  or  in  such  and  such  a  way;  because 
the  greater  the  number  of  conditions  added,  the  greater  the 
number  of  ways  in  which  the  principle  may  fail,  so  that  it 
be  not  right  to  restore  or  not  to  restore. 

Consequently  we  must  say  that  the  natural  law,  as  to 
general  principles,  is  the  same  for  all,  both  as  to  rectitude 
and  as  to  knowledge.  But  as  to  certain  matters  of  detail, 
which  are  conclusions,  as  i4!  vvfft,  of  those  general  principles, 
it  is  the  same  for  all  in  the  majority  of  cases,  both  as  to 
rectitude  and  as  to  knowledge ;  and  yet  in  some  few  cases  it 
may  fail,  both  as  to  rectitude,  by  reason  of  certain  obstacles 
(just  as  natures  subject  to  generation  and  corruption  fail  in 
some  few  cases  on  account  of  some  obstacle),  and  as  to 
knowledge,  since  in  some  the  reason  is  perverted  by  passion, 
or  evil  habit,  or  an  evil  disposition  of  nature ;  thus  formerly, 
theft,  although  it  is  expressly  contrary  to  the  natural  law, 
was  not  considered  wrong  among  the  Germans,  as  Julius 
Caesar  relates  {De  Bello  Gall.  vi.). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  meaning  of  the  sentence  quoted  is 
not  that  whatever  is  contained  in  the  Law  and  the  Gospel 


49  THE  NATURAL  LAW  g.  94.  Art.  5 

belongs  to  the  natural  law,  since  they  contain  many  things 
that  are  above  nature;  but  that  whatever  belongs  to  the 
natural  law  is  fully  contained  in  them.  Wherefore  Gratian, 
after  sa^ang  that  the  natural  law  is  what  is  contained  in  the 
Law  and  the  Gospel,  adds  at  once,  by  way  of  example,  by 
which  everyone  is  commanded  to  do  to  others  as  he  would  be 
done  by. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  saying  of  the  Philosopher  is  to  be  under- 
stood of  things  that  are  naturally  just,  not  as  general 
principles,  but  as  conclusions  drawn  from  them,  having 
rectitude  in  the  majority  of  cases,  but  failing  in  a  few. 

Reply  Obj,  3.  As,  in  man,  reason  rules  and  commands  the 
other  powers,  so  all  the  natural  inclinations  belonging  to  the 
other  powers  must  needs  be  directed  according  to  reason. 
Wherefore  it  is  universally  right  for  all  men,  that  all  their 
inclinations  should  be  directed  according  to  reason. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  the  natural  law  can  be  changed  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  natural  law  can  be  changed. 
Because  on  Ecclus.  xvii.  q,  He  gave  them  instructions,  and 
the  law  of  life,  the  gloss  says :  He  wished  the  law  of  the  letter 
to  be  written,  in  order  to  correct  the  law  of  nature.  But  that 
which  is  corrected  is  changed.  Therefore  the  natural  law 
can  be  changed. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  slaying  of  the  innocent,  adultery,  and 
theft  are  against  the  natural  law.  But  we  find  these  things 
changed  by  God :  as  when  God  commanded  Abraham  to  slay 
his  innocent  son  (Gen.  xxii.  2) ;  and  when  He  ordered  the 
Jews  to  borrow  and  purloin  the  vessels  of  the  Egyptians 
(Exod.  xh.  35) ;  and  when  He  commanded  Osee  to  take  to 
himself  a  wife  of  fornications  [Osee  i.  2).  Therefore  the 
natural  law  can  be  changed. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Isidore  says  (Etym.  v.)  that  the  possession 
of  all  things  in  common,  and  universal  freedom,  are  matters  of 
natural  law.     But  these  things  are  seen  to  be  changed  by 

n-3  4 


Q.  94.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  50 

human  laws.     Therefore  it  seems  that  the  natural  law  is 
subject  to  change. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  said  in  the  Decretals  {Dist.  v.) :  The 
natural  law  dates  from  the  creation  of  the  rational  creature. 
It  does  not  vary  according  to  time,  hut  remains  unchangeable. 

I  answer  that,  A  change  in  the  natural  law  may  be  imder- 
stood  in  two  ways.  First,  by  way  of  addition.  In  this 
sense  nothing  hinders  the  natural  law  from  being  changed: 
since  many  things  for  the  benefit  of  human  life  have  been 
added  over  and  above  the  natural  law,  both  by  the  Divine 
law  and  by  human  laws. 

Secondly,  a  change  in  the  natural  law  may  be  understood 
by  way  of  subtraction,  so  that  what  previously  was  according 
to  the  natural  law,  ceases  to  be  so.  In  this  sense,  the  natural 
law  is  altogether  unchangeable  in  its  first  principles:  but  in 
its  secondary  principles,  which,  as  we  have  said  (A.  4),  are 
certain  detailed  proximate  conclusions  drawn  from  the  first 
principles,  the  natural  law  is  not  changed  so  that  what  it 
prescribes  be  not  right  in  most  cases.  But  it  may  be  changed 
in  some  particular  cases  of  rare  occurrence,  through  some 
special  causes  hindering  the  observance  of  such  precepts,  as 
stated  above  (A.  4). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  written  law  is  said  to  be  given  for  the 
correction  of  the  natural  law,  either  because  it  supplies 
what  was  wanting  to  the  natural  law;  or  because  the  natural 
law  was  perverted  in  the  hearts  of  some  men,  as  to  certain 
matters,  so  that  they  esteemed  those  things  good  which  are 
naturally  evil ;  which  perversion  stood  in  need  of  correction. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  All  men  alike,  both  guilty  and  innocent,  die 
the  death  of  nature :  which  death  of  nature  is  inflicted  by  the 
power  of  God  on  account  of  original  sin,  according  to 
I  Kings  ii.  6:  The  Lord  killeth  and  maketh  alive.  Conse- 
quently, by  the  command  of  God,  death  can  be  inflicted  on 
any  man,  guilty  or  innocent,  without  any  injustice  whatever. 
— In  like  manner  adultery  is  intercourse  with  another's  wife ; 
who  is  allotted  to  him  by  the  law  emanating  from  God. 
Consequently  intercourse  with  any  woman,  by  the  command 
of  God,  is  neither  adultery  nor  fornication. — The  same  applies 


51  THE  NATURAL  LAW  Q.  94.  Art.  5 

to  theft,  which  is  the  taking  of  another's  property.  For 
whatever  is  taken  by  the  command  of  God,  to  Whom  all 
things  belong,  is  not  taken  against  the  will  of  its  owner, 
whereas  it  is  in  this  that  theft  consists. — -Nor  is  it  only  in 
human  things,  that  whatever  is  commanded  by  dod  is 
right ;  but  also  in  natural  things,  whatever  is  done  by  dod,  is, 
in  some  way,  natural,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  CV., 
A.  6  ad  1). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  A  thing  is  said  to  belong  to  the  natural  law 
in  two  ways.  First,  because  nature  inclines  thereto:  e.g., 
that  one  should  not  do  harm  to  another.  Secondly,  because 
nature  did  not  bring  in  the  contrary:  thus  we  might  say  Ihat 
for  man  to  be  naked  is  of  the  natural  law,  because  nature  did 
not  give  him  clothes,  but  art  invented  them.  In  this  sense, 
the  possession  of  all  things  in  common  and  universal  freedom 
are  said  to  be  of  the  natural  law,  because,  to  wit,  the  dis- 
tinction of  possessions  and  slavery  were  not  brought  in  by 
nature,  but  devised  by  human  reason  for  the  benefit  of 
human  life.  Accordingly  the  law  of  nature  was  not  changed 
in  this  respect,  except  by  addition. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  the  law^  of  nature  can  be  abolished 
from  the  heart  of  man  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  natural  law  can  be  abolished 
from  the  heart  of  man.  Because  on  Rom.  ii.  14,  When  the 
Gentiles  who  have  not  the  law,  etc.,  the  gloss  says  that  the  law 
of  righteousness,  which  sin  had  blotted  out,  is  graven  on  the 
heart  of  man  when  he  is  restored  by  grace.  But  the  law  of 
righteousness  is  the  law  of  nature.  Therefore  the  law  of 
nature  can  be  blotted  out. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  law  of  grace  is  more  efficacious  than 
the  law  of  nature.  But  the  law  of  grace  is  blotted  out  by  sin. 
Much  more  therefore  can  the  law  of  nature  be  blotted  out. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  that  which  is  established  by  law  is  made 
just.     But  many  things  are  enacted  by  men,  which   are 


g.  94.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  52 

contrary  to  the  law  of  nature.  Therefore  the  law  of  nature 
can  be  abolished  from  the  heart  of  man. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {Conf.  ii.) :  Thy  law  is 
written  in  the  hearts  of  men,  which  iniquity  itself  effaces  not. 
But  the  law  which  is  written  in  men's  hearts  is  the  natural 
law.     Therefore  the  natural  law  cannot  be  blotted  out. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (AA.  4,  5),  there  belong  to 
the  natural  law,  first,  certain  most  general  precepts,  that  are 
known  to  all;  and  secondly,  certain  secondary  and  more 
detailed  precepts,  which  are,  as  it  were,  conclusions  following 
closely  from  first  principles.  As  to  those  general  principles,  the 
natural  law,  in  the  abstract,  can  nowise  be  blotted  out  from 
men's  hearts.  But  it  is  blotted  out  in  the  case  of  a  par- 
ticular action,  in  so  far  as  reason  is  hindered  from  applying 
the  general  principle  to  a  particular  point  of  practice,  on 
account  of  concupiscence  or  some  other  passion,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  LXXVIL,  A.  2). — But  as  to  the  other,  i.e.,  the 
secondary  precepts,  the  natural  law  can  be  blotted  out  from 
the  human  heart,  either  by  evil  persuasions,  just  as  in  specu- 
lative matters  errors  occur  in  respect  of  necessary  conclu- 
sions; or  by  vicious  customs  and  corrupt  habits,  as  among 
some  men,  theft,  and  even  unnatural  vices,  as  the  Apostle 
states  (Rom.  i.),  were  not  esteemed  sinful. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Sin  blots  out  the  law  of  nature  in  particular 
cases,  not  universally,  except  perchance  in  regard  to  the 
secondary  precepts  of  the  natural  law,  in  the  way  stated 
above. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  grace  is  more  efficacious  than 
nature,  yet  nature  is  more  essential  to  man,  and  therefore 
more  enduring. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  argument  is  true  of  the  secondary 
precepts  of  the  natural  law,  against  which  some  legislators 
have  framed  certain  enactments  which  are  unjust. 


QUESTION  XCV. 

OF    HUMAN    LAW. 

{In  Four  Articles. ) 

We  must  now  consider  human  law;  and  (i)  this  law  con- 
sidered in  itself;  (2)  its  power;  (3)  its  mutability.     Under 
the  first  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Its  utiHty 
(2)  Its  origin.     (3)  Its  quality.     (4)  Its  division. 

First  Article, 
whether  it  was  useful  for  laws  to  be  framed 

BY    MEN  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  it  was  not  useful  for  laws  to  be 
framed  by  men.  Because  the  purpose  of  every  law  is  that 
man  be  made  good  thereby,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCIL,  A.  i). 
But  men  are  more  to  be  induced  to  be  good  willingly  by 
means  of  admonitions,  than  against  their  will,  by  means  of 
laws.     Therefore  there  was  no  need  to  frame  laws. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  As  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  v.),  men 
have  recourse  to  a  judge  as  to  animate  justice.  But  animate 
justice  is  better  than  inanimate  justice,  which  is  contained 
in  laws.  Therefore  it  would  have  been  better  for  the  execu- 
tion of  justice  to  be  entrusted  to  the  decision  of  judges, 
than  to  frame  laws  in  addition. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  every  law  is  framed  for  the  direction  of 
human  actions,  as  is  evident  from  what  has  been  stated 
above  (Q.  XC,  A  A.  i,  2).  But  since  human  actions  are 
about  singulars,  which  are  infinite  in  number,  matters  per- 
taining to  the  direction  of  human  actions  cannot  be  taken 

53 


Q.  95.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOrxICA  "  54 

into  sufficient  consideration  except  by  a  wise  man,  who 
looks  into  each  one  of  them.  Therefore  it  would  have 
been  better  for  human  acts  to  be  directed  by  the  judgment 
of  wise  men,  than  by  the  framing  of  laws.  Therefore  there 
was  no  need  of  hu^an  laws. 

On  the  contrary,  Isidore  says  {Etym.  v.) :  Laws  were  fuade 
that  in  fear  thereof  human  audacity  might  he  held  in  check, 
that  innocence  might  he  safeguarded  in  the  midst  of  wickedness , 
and  that  the  dread  of  punishment  might  prevent  the  wicked 
from  doing  harm.  But  these  things  are  most  necessary  to 
mankind.  Therefore  it  was  necessary  that  human  laws 
should  be  made. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  LXIIL,  A.  i ;  Q.  XCIV., 
A.  3),  man  has  a  natural  aptitude  for  virtue;  but  the  per- 
fection of  virtue  must  be  acquired  by  man  by  means  of  some 
kind  of  training.  Thus  we  observe  that  man  is  helped  by 
industry  in  his  necessities,  for  instance,  in  food  and  clothing. 
Certain  beginnings  of  these  he  has  from  nature,  viz.,  his 
reason  and  his  hands ;  but  he  has  not  the  full  complement,  as 
other  animals  have,  to  whom  nature  has  given  sufficiency  of 
clothing  and  food.  Now  it  is  difficult  to  see  how  man  could 
suffice  for  himself  in  the  matter  of  this  training:  since  the 
perfection  of  virtue  consists  chiefly  in  withdrawing  man 
from  undue  pleasures,  to  which  above  all  man  is  inclined, 
and  especially  the  young,  who  are  more  capable  of  being 
trained.  Consequently  a  man  needs  to  receive  this  training 
from  another,  whereby  to  arrive  at  the  perfection  of  virtue. 
And  as  to  those  young  people  who  are  inclined  to  acts  of 
virtue,  by  their  good  natural  disposition,  or  by  custom,  or 
rather  by  the  gift  of  God,  paternal  training  suffices,  which 
is  by  admonitions.  But  since  some  are  found  to  be  depraved, 
and  prone  to  vice,  and  not  easily  amenable  to  words,  it  was 
necessary  for  such  to  be  restrained  from  evil  by  force  and 
fear,  in  order  that,  at  least,  they  might  desist  from  evil-doing, 
and  leave  others  in  peace,  and  that  they  themselves,  by  being 
habituated  in  this  way,  might  be  brought  to  do  willingly 
what  hitherto  they  did  from  fear,  and  thus  become  virtuous. 
Now  this  kind  of  training,  v/hich  compels  through  fear  of 


55  HUMAN  LAW  Q.95.ART.  i 

punishment,  is  the  disciphne  of  laws.  Therefore,  in  order 
that  man  might  have  peace  and  virtue,  it  was  necessary  for 
laws  to  be  framed:  for,  as  the  Philosopher  says  [Polit.  i.), 
as  man  is  the  most  noble  of  animals  if  he  he  perfect  in  virtue, 
so  is  he  the  lowest  of  all,  if  he  he  severed  from  law  and  righteous- 
ness  ;  because  man  can  use  his  reason  to  devise  means  of 
satisfying  his  lusts  and  evil  passions,  which  other  animals 
are  unable  to  do. 

Reply  Ohj,  i.  Men  who  are  well  disposed  are  led  willingly 
to  virtue  by  being  admonished  better  than  by  coercion :  but 
men  who  are  evilly  disposed  are  not  led  to  virtue  unless 
they  are  compelled. 

Reply  Ohj,  2.  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  i.),  it  is  hetter 
that  all  things  he  regulated  hy  law,  than  left  to  he  decided  hy 
judges  :  and  this  for  three  reasons.  First,  because  it  is 
easier  to  find  a  few  wise  men  competent  to  frame  right  laws, 
than  to  find  the  many  who  would  be  necessary  to  judge 
aright  of  each  single  case. — Secondly,  because  those  who 
make  laws  consider  long  beforehand  what  laws  to  make; 
whereas  judgment  on  each  single  case  has  to  be  pronounced 
as  soon  as  it  arises:  and  it  is  easier  for  man  to  see  what  is 
right,  by  taking  many  instances  into  consideration,  than 
by  considering  one  solitary  fact. — Thirdly,  because  law- 
givers judge  in  the  abstract  and  of  future  events;  whereas 
those  who  sit  in  judgment  judge  of  things  present,  towards 
which  they  are  affected  by  love,  hatred,  or  some  kind  of 
cupidity;  wherefore  their  judgment  is  perverted. 

Since  then  the  animated  justice  of  the  judge  is  not  found 
in  every  man,  and  since  it  can  be  deflected,  therefore  it  was 
necessary,  whenever  possible,  for  the  law  to  determine  how 
to  judge,  and  for  very  few  matters  to  be  left  to  the  decision 
of  men. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Certain  individual  facts  which  cannot  be 
covered  by  the  law  have  necessarily  to  he  committed  to  judges, 
as  the  Philosopher  says  in  the  same  passage:  for  instance, 
concerning  something  that  has  happened  or  not  happened,  and 
the  like. 


Q.  95-  Art.  2      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  56 


X 


Second  Article. 


WHETHER    EVERY    HUMAN    LAW   IS    DERIVED    FROM    THE 

NATURAL   LAW  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  not  every  human  law  is  derived 
from  the  natural  law.  For  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  v.) 
that  the  legal  just  is  that  which  originally  was  a  matter  of 
indifference.  But  those  things  which  arise  from  the  natural 
law  are  not  matters  of  indifference.  Therefore  the  enact- 
ments of  human  laws  are  not  all  derived  from  the  natural 
law. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  positive  law  is  contrasted  with  natural 
law,  as  stated  by  Isidore  {Etym.  v.)  and  the  Philosopher 
(Ethic,  v.).  But  those  things  which  flow  as  conclusions 
from  the  general  principles  of  the  natural  law  belong  to  the 
natural  law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCIV.,  A.  4).  Therefore 
that  which  is  established  by  human  law  does  not  belong  to 
the  natural  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  law  of  nature  is  the  same  for  all; 
since  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  v.)  that  the  natural  just 
is  that  which  is  equally  valid  everywhere.  If  therefore  human 
laws  were  derived  from  the  natural  law,  it  would  follow 
that  they  too  are  the  same  for  all:  which  is  clearly  false. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  it  is  possible  to  give  a  reason  for  things 
which  are  derived  from  the  natural  law.  But  it  is  not 
possible  to  give  the  reason  for  all  the  legal  enactments  of  the 
lawgivers  (Pandect.  Justin.  Lib.  I.,  Tit.  III.,  Art  V.,  De 
legibus,  etc.).  Therefore  not  all  human  laws  are  derived 
from  the  natural  law. 

On  the  contrary,  TuUy  says  (Rhetor,  ii.) :  Things  which 
emanated  from  nature  and  were  approved  by  custom,  were 
sanctioned  by  fear  and  reverence  for  the  laws. 

I  answer  that,  As  Augustine  says  (De  Lib.  Arb.  i.),  that 
which  is  not  just  seems  to  be  no  law  at  all :  wherefore  the 
force  of  a  law  depends  on  the  extent  of  its  justice.  Now 
inhuman  affairs  a  thing  is  said  to  be  just,  from  being  right, 


57  HUMAN  LAW  Q.  95.  Art.  2 

according  to  the  rule  of  reason.  But  the  first  rule  of  reason 
is  the  law  of  nature,  as  is  clear  from  what  has  been  stated 
above  (0.  XCL,  A.  2  ad  2).  Consequently  every  human 
law  has  iust  so  much  of  the  nature  of  law,  as  it  is  derived 
from  the  law  of  nature.  But  if  in  any  point  it  deflects 
from  the  law  of  nature,  it  is  no  longer  a  law  but  a  perversion 
of  law. 

But  it  must  be  noted  that  something  may  be  derived 
fix)m  the  natural  law  in  twoways:  first,  as  a  conclusion 
from  premisses,  secondly,  by  way  of  defermination  of  certain 
generalities.  The  firsl:  way  is  like  to  that  by  which,  in 
sciences,  demonstrated  conclusions  are  drawn  from  the 
principles:  while  the  second  mode  is  hkened  to  that  whereby, 
in  the  arts,  general  forms  are  particularized  as  to  details: 
thus  the  craftsman  needs  to  determine  the  general  form  of 
a  house  to  some  particular  shape.  Some  things  are  there- 
fore derived  from  the  general  principles  of  the  natural  law, 
by  way  of  conclusions;  e.g.,  that  one  must  not  kill  may  be 
derived  as  a  conclusion  from  the  principle  that  one  should 
do  harm  to  no  man  :  while  some  are  derived  therefrom  by 
way  of  determination;  e.g.,  the  law  of  nature  has  it  that  the 
evil-doer  should  be  punished;  but  that  he  be  punished  in  this 
or  that  way,  is  a  determination  of  the  law  of  nature. 

Accordingly  both  modes  of  derivation  are  found  in  the 
human  law.  But  those  things  which  are  derived  in  the 
first  way,  are  contained  in  human  law  not  as  emanating 
therefrom  exclusively,  but  have  some  force  from  the  natural 
law  also.  But  those  things  which  are  derived  in  the  second 
way,  have  no  other  force  than  that  of  human  law. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  Philosopher  is  speaking  of  those  enact- 
ments which  are  by  way  of  determination  or  specification 
of  the  precepts  of  the  natural  law. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  argument  avails  for  those  things  that 
are  derived  from  the  natural  law,  by  way  of  conclusions. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  general  principles  of  the  natural  law 
cannot  be  applied  to  all  men  in  the  same  way  on  account  of 
the  great  variety  of  human  affairs:  and  hence  arises  the 
diversity  of  positive  laws  among  various  people. 


Q.  95.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  58 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  These  words  of  the  Jurist  are  to  be  under- 
stood as  referring  to  decisions  of  rulers  in  determining 
particular  points  of  the  natural  law :  on  which  determina- 
tions the  judgment  of  expert  and  prudent  men  is  based  as 
on  its  principles;  in  so  far,  to  wit,  as  they  see  at  once  what 
is  the  best  thing  to  decide. 

Hence  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  vi.)  that  in  such 
matters,  we  ought  to  pay  as  much  attention  to  the  un- 
demonstrated  sayings  and  opinions  of  persons  who  surpass 
us  in  experience,  age  and  prudence,  as  to  their  demonstrations. 

Third  Article. 
WHETHER  Isidore's  description  of  the  quality  of 

POSITIVE   LAW   IS   APPROPRIATE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  Isidore's  description  of  the 
quality  of  positive  law  is  not  appropriate,  when  he  says: 
Law  shall  be  virtuous,  just,  possible  to  nature,  according  to 
the  custom  of  the  country,  suitable  to  place  and  time,  necessary, 
useful ;  clearly  expressed,  lest  by  its  obscurity  it  lead  to  mis- 
understanding; framed  for  no  private  benefit,  but  for  the  cor/imon 
good  of  the  people.  Because  he  had  previously  expressed 
the  quality  of  law  in  three  conditions,  saying  that  law  is 
anything  founded  on  reason,  provided  that  it  foster  religion, 
be  helpful  to  discipline,  and  further  the  common  weal.  There- 
fore it  was  needless  to  add  any  further  conditions  to  these. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Justice  is  included  in  honesty,  as  Tully 
says  [De  Offic.  vii.).  Therefore  after  saying  honest  it  was 
superfluous  to  add  just. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  written  law  is  condivided  with  custom, 
according  to  Isidore  [Etym.  ii.).  Therefore  it  should  not  be 
stated  in  the  definition  of  law  that  it  is  according  to  the 
custom  of  the  country. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  a  thing  may  be  necessary  in  two  ways. 
It  may  be  necessary  simply,  because  it  cannot  be  otherwise: 
and  that  which  is  necessary  in  this  way,  is  not  subject  to 
human  judgment,  wherefore  human  law  is  not  concerned 


59  HUMAN  LAW  Q-95Art.  3 

with  necessity  of  this  kind.  Again  a  thing  may  be  neces- 
sary for  an  end:  and  this  necessity  is  the  same  as  usefuhiess. 
Therefore  it  is  superfluous  to  say  both  necessary  and  useful. 

On  the  contrary  stands  the  authority  of  Isidore. 

/  answer  that,  Whenever  a  thing  is  for  an  end,  its  form 
must  be  determined  proportionately  to  that  end;  as  the 
form  of  a  saw  is  such  as  to  be  suitable  for  cutting  (Phys.  ii.). 
Again,  everything  that  is  ruled  and  measured  must  have  a 
form  proportionate  to  its  rule  and  measure.  Now  both 
these  conditions  are  verified  of  human  law:  since  it  is  both 
something  ordained  to  an  end;  and  is  a  rule  or  measure 
ruled  or  measured  by  a  higher  measure.  And  this  higher 
measure  is  twofold,  viz.,  the  Divine  law  and  the  natural 
law,  as  explained  above  (A.  2;  Q.  XCIII.,  A.  3).  Now 
the  end  of  human  law  is  to  be  useful  to  man,  as  the  Jurist 
states  {Pandect.  Just.  i.).  Wherefore  Isidore  in  deter- 
mining the  nature  of  law,  lays  down,  at  first,  three  con- 
ditions; viz.,  that  it  foster  religion,  inasmuch  as  it  is  pro- 
portionate to  the  Divine  law;  that  it  be  helpful  to  discipline, 
inasmuch  as  it  is  proportionate  to  the  natural  law;  and  that 
it  further  the  common  weal,  inasmuch  as  it  is  proportionate 
to  the  utility  of  mankind. 

All  the  other  conditions  mentioned  by  him  are  reduced 
to  these  three.  For  it  is  called  virtuous  because  it  fosters 
religion.  And  when  he  goes  on  to  say  that  it  should 
be  just,  possible  to  nature,  according  to  the  customs  of 
the  country,  adapted  to  place  and  time,  he  implies  that  it 
should  be  helpful  to  discipline.  For  human  discipline 
depends  first  on  the  order  of  reason,  to  which  he  refers  by 
saying  just : — secondly,  it  depends  on  the  ability  of  the 
agent;  because  discipline  should  be  adapted  to  each  one 
according  to  his  ability,  taking  also  into  account  the 
ability  of  nature  (for  the  same  burdens  should  be  not  laid  on 
children  as  on  adults) ;  and  should  be  according  to  human 
customs;  since  man  cannot  live  alone  in  society,  paying  no 
heed  to  others: — thirdly,  it  depends  on  certain  circum- 
stances, in  respect  of  which  he  says,  adapted  to  place  and 
time. — The   remaining  words,   necessary,  useful,  etc.,  mean 


Q.  95.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGTCA  "  60 

that  law  should  further  the  common  weal:  so  that  necessity 
refers  to  the  removal  of  evils;  usefulness  to  the  attainment 
of  good;  clearness  of  expression,  to  the  need  of  preventing 
any  harm  ensuing  from  the  law  itself. — And  since,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2),  law  is  ordained  to  the  common  good, 
this  is  expressed  in  the  last  part  of  the  description. 
This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Objections. 


Fourth  Article. 
WHETHER  Isidore's  division  of  human  laws  is 

APPROPRIATE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  Isidore  wrongly  divided  human 
statutes  or  human  law  [Etym.  v.).  For  under  this  law  he 
includes  the  law  of  nations,  so  called,  because,  as  he  says, 
nearly  all  nations  use  it.  But  as  he  says,  natural  law  is  that 
which  is  common  to  all  nations.  Therefore  the  law  of  nations 
is  not  contained  under  positive  human  law,  but  rather 
under  natural  law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  those  laws  which  have  the  same  force, 
seem  to  differ  not  formally  but  only  materially.  But 
statutes,  decrees  of  the  commonalty,  senatorial  decrees,  and  the 
like  which  he  mentions,  all  have  the  same  force.  Therefore 
they  do  not  differ,  except  materially.  But  art  takes  no 
notice  of  such  a  distinction:  since  it  may  go  on  to  infinity. 
Therefore  this  division  of  human  laws  is  not  appropriate. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  just  as,  in  the  state,  there  are  princes, 
priests  and  soldiers,  so  are  there  other  human  offices.  There- 
fore it  seems  that,  as  this  division  includes  military  law,  and 
public  law,  referring  to  priests  and  magistrates;  so  also  it 
should  include  other  laws  pertaining  to  other  offices  of  the 
state. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  those  things  that  are  accidental  should 
be  passed  over.  But  it  is  accidental  to  law  that  it  be  framed 
by  this  or  that  man.  Therefore  it  is  unreasonable  to  divide 
laws  according  to  the  names  of  lawgivers,  so  that  one  be 
called  the  Cornelian  law,  another  the  Falcidiun  law,  etc. 


6i  HUMAN  LAW  o.  95.  Art.  4 

On  the  contrary,  The  authority  of  Isidon;  suihces. 

/  answer  that,  A  thing  can  of  itself  be  divided  in  respect 
of  something  contained  in  the  notion  of  that  thing.  Thus  a 
soul  either  rational  or  irrational  is  contained  in  the  notion 
of  animal:  and  therefore  animal  is  divided  properly  and 
of  itself  in  respect  of  its  being  rational  or  irrational;  but  not 
in  the  point  of  its  being  white  or  black,  which  are  entirely 
beside  the  notion  of  animal.  Now,  in  the  notion  of  human 
law,  many  things  are  contained,  in  respect  of  any  of  which 
human  law  can  be  divided  properly  and  of  itself.  For  in 
the  first  place  it  belongs  to  the  notion  of  human  law,  to  be 
derived  from  the  law  of  nature,  as  explained  above  (A.  2). 
In  this  respect  positive  law  is  divided  into  the  law  of  nations 
and  civil  law,  according  to  the  two  ways  in  which  some- 
thing may  be  derived  from  the  law  of  nature,  as  stated 
above  (A.  2).  Because,  to  the  law  of  nations  belong  those 
things  which  are  derived  from  the  law  of  nature,  as  conclu- 
sions from  premisses,  e.g.,  just  buyings  and  sellings,  and  the 
like,  without  which  men  cannot  live  together,  which  is  a 
point  of  the  law  of  nature,  since  man  is  by  nature  a  social 
animal,  as  is  proved  in  Polit.  i.  But  those  things  which  are 
derived  from  the  law  of  nature  by  way  of  particular  deter- 
mination, belong  to  the  civil  law,  according  as  each  state 
decides  on  what  is  best  for  itself. 

Secondly,  it  belongs  to  the  notion  of  human  law,  to  be 
ordained  to  the  common  good  of  the  state.  In  this  respect 
human  law  may  be  divided  according  to  the  different  kinds 
of  men  who  work  in  a  special  way  for  the  common  good: 
e.g.,  priests,  by  praying  to  God  for  the  people;  princes,  by 
governing  the  people;  soldiers,  by  fighting  for  the  safety 
of  the  people.  Wherefore  certain  special  kinds  of  law  are 
adapted  to  these  men. 

Thirdly,  it  belongs  to  the  notion  of  human  law,  to  be 
framed  by  that  one  who  governs  the  community  of  the 
state,  as  shown  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  3).  In  this  respect, 
there  are  various  human  laws  according  to  the  various 
forms  of  government.  Of  these,  according  to  the  Philosopher 
(Polit.  iii.)  one  is  monarchy,  i.e.,  when  the  state  is  governed 


Q.  95.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THP:OLOGICA  "  62 

by  one ;  and  then  we  have  Royal  Ordinances.  Another  form 
is  aristocracy,  i.e.,  government  by  the  best  men  or  men  of 
highest  rank;  and  then  we  have  the  Authoritative  legal 
opinions  (Responsa  Prudentum)  and  Decrees  of  the  Senate 
{Senatus  consiilta).  Another  form  is  oligarchy,  i.e.,  govern- 
ment by  a  few  rich  and  powerful  men;  and  then  we  have 
Prcetorian,  also  called  Honorary,  law.  Another  form  of 
government  is  that  of  the  people,  which  is  called  democracy, 
and  there  we  have  Decrees  of  the  commonalty  [Plehiscita) . 
There  is  also  tyrannical  government,  which  is  altogether 
corrupt,  which,  therefore,  has  no  corresponding  law.  Finally, 
there  is  a  form  of  government  made  up  of  all  these,  and 
which  is  the  best:  and  in  this  respect  we  have  law 
sanctioned  by  the  Lords  and  Commons,  as  stated  by  Isidore 
[loc.  cit). 

Fourthly,  it  belongs  to  the  notion  of  human  law  to  direct 
humxan  actions.  In  this  respect,  according  to  the  various 
matters  of  which  the  law  treats,  there  are  various  kinds  of 
laws,  which  are  sometimes  named  after  their  authors:  thus 
we  have  the  Lex  Julia  about  adultery,  the  Lex  Cornelia 
concerning  assassins,  and  so  on,  differentiated  in  this  way, 
not  on  account  of  the  authors,  but  on  account  of  the  matters 
to  which  they  refer. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  law  of  nations  is  indeed,  in  some  way, 
natural  to  man,  in  so  far  as  he  is  a  reasonable  being,  because 
it  is  derived  from  the  natural  law  by  way  of  a  conclusion 
that  is  not  very  remote  from  its  premisses.  Wherefore  men 
easily  agreed  thereto.  Nevertheless  it  is  distinct  from  the 
natural  law,  especially  from  that  natural  law  which  is 
common  to  all  animals. 

The  Replies  to  the  other  Objections  are  evident  from  what 
has  been  said. 


QUESTION  XCVI. 

OF  THE  POWER  OF  HUMAN  LAW. 

{In  Six  Articles.) 

W'e  must  now  consider  the  power  of  human  law.  Under  this 
head  there  are  six  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  human  law 
should  be  framed  for  the  community  ?  (2)  Whether  human 
law  should  repress  all  vices  ?  (3)  Whether  human  law  is 
competent  to  direct  all  acts  of  virtue  ?  (4)  Whether  it 
binds  man  in  conscience  ?  (5)  Whether  all  men  are  subject 
to  human  law  ?  (6)  Whether  those  who  are  under  the  law 
may  act  beside  the  letter  of  the  law  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  human  law  should  be  framed  for  the 
community  rather  than  for  the  individual  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  human  law  should  be  framed 
not  for  the  community,  but  rather  for  the  individual.  For 
the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  v.)  that  the  legal  just .  .  .  includes 
all  particular  acts  oj  legislation  .  .  .  and  all  those  matters 
which  are  the  subject  of  decrees,  which  are  also  individual 
matters,  since  decrees  are  framed  about  individual  actions. 
Therefore  law  is  framed  not  only  for  the  community,  but  also 
for  the  individual. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  law  is  the  director  of  human  acts,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A  A.  i,  2).  But  human  acts  are 
about  individual  matters.  Therefore  human  laws  should  be 
framed,  not  for  the  community,  but  rather  for  the  indi- 
vidual. 

t^3 


Q.  96.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  64 

Obj.  3.  Further,  law  is  a  rule  and  measure  of  human  acts, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A  A.  i,  2).  But  a  measure  should 
be  most  certain,  as  stated  in  Metaph.  x.  Since  therefore  in 
human  acts  no  general  proposition  can  be  so  certain  as  not 
to  fail  in  some  individual  cases,  it  seems  that  laws  should 
be  framed  not  in  general  but  for  individual  cases. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Jurist  says  [Pandect.  Justin.  Lib.  I., 
Tit.  IIL,  Art  II.,  De  legihus,  etc.)  that  laws  should  he  made 
to  suit  the  majority  of  instances  ;  and  they  are  not  framed 
according  to  what  may  possibly  happen  in  an  individual  case. 

I  answer  that,  Whatever  is  for  an  end  should  be  propor- 
tionate to  that  end.  Now  the  end  of  law  is  the  common 
good;  because,  as  Isidore  says  (Etym.  ii.)  that  law  should  be 
framed,  not  for  any  private  benefit,  but  for  the  common  good  of 
all  the  citizens.  Hence  human  laws  should  be  proportionate 
to  the  common  good.  Now  the  common  good  comprises 
many  things.  Wherefore  law  should  take  account  of  many 
things,  as  to  persons,  as  to  matters,  and  as  to  times.  Be- 
cause the  community  of  the  state  is  composed  of  many 
persons ;  and  its  good  is  procured  by  many  actions ;  nor  is  it 
established  to  endure  for  only  a  short  time,  but  to  last 
for  all  time  by  the  citizens  succeeding  one  another,  as 
Augustine  says  {De  Civ.  Dei  xxii.). 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  Philosopher  [Ethic,  v.)  divides  the  legal 
just,  i.e.,  positive  law,  into  three  parts.  For  some  things  are 
laid  down  simply  in  a  general  way:  and  these  are  the  general 
laws.  Of  these  he  says  that  the  legal  is  that  which  originally 
was  a  matter  of  indifference,  but  which,  when  enacted,  is  so 
no  longer  :  as  the  fixing  of  the  ransom  of  a  captive. — Some 
things  affect  the  community  in  one  respect,  and  individuals 
in  another.  These  are  called  privileges,  i.e.,  private  laws,  as 
it  were,  because  they  regard  private  persons,  although  their 
power  extends  to  many  matters;  and  in  regard  to  these,  he 
adds,  and  further,  all  particular  acts  of  legislation. — Other 
matters  are  legal,  not  through  being  laws,  but  through  being 
applications  of  general  laws  to  particular  cases:  such  are 
decrees  which  have  the  force  of  law;  and  in  regard  to  these, 
he  adds  all  matters  subject  to  decrees. 


65  THE  POWER  OF  HUMAN  LAW     Q.  96.  Art.  i 

Reply  Obj.  2.  A  principle  of  direction  should  be  applic- 
able to  many;  wherefore  {Metaph.  x.)  the  Philosopher  says 
that  all  things  belonging  to  one  genus,  are  measured  by 
one,  which  is  the  principle  in  that  genus.  For  if  there  were 
as  many  rules  or  measures  as  there  are  things  measured 
or  ruled,  they  would  cease  to  be  of  use,  since  their  use 
consists  in  being  applicable  to  many  things.  Hence  law 
would  be  of  no  use,  if  it  did  not  extend  further  than  to  one 
single  act.  Because  the  decrees  of  prudent  men  are  made 
for  the  purpose  of  directing  individual  actions ;  whereas  law 
is  a  general  precept,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCIL,  A.  2,  Obj.  2). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  We  must  not  seek  the  same  degree  of  certainty 
in  all  things  {Ethic,  i.).  Consequently  in  contingent  matters, 
such  as  natural  and  human  things,  it  is  enough  for  a  thing 
to  be  certain,  as  being  true  in  the  greater  number  of  in- 
stances, though  at  times  and  less  frequently  it  fail. 


X 


Second  Article. 


WHETHER    IT    BELONGS    TO    HUMAN    LAW    TO    REPRESS 

ALL   VICES  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  it  belongs  to  human  law  to 
repress  all  vices.  For  Isidore  says  (Etym.  v.)  that  laws 
were  made  in  order  that,  in  fear  thereof,  man''s  audacity  might 
be  held  in  check.  But  it  would  not  be  held  in  check  suffi- 
ciently, unless  all  evils  were  repressed  by  law.  Therefore 
human  law  should  repress  all  evils. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver  is  to  make 
the  citizens  virtuous.  But  a  man  cannot  be  virtuous  unless 
he  forbear  from  all  kinds  of  vice.  Therefore  it  belongs  to 
human  law  to  repress  all  vices. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  human  law  is  derived  from  the  natural 
law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCV.,  A.  2).  But  all  vices  are 
contrary  to  the  law  of  nature.  Therefore  human  law  should 
repress  all  vices. 

On  the  contrary.  We  read  in  De  Lib.  Arb.  i. :  It  seems  to  me 
that  the  law  which  is  written  for  the  governing  of  the  people 

".3  5 


Q.  96.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGTCA  "  66 

rightly  permits  these  things,  and  that  Divine  providence 
punishes  them.  But  Divine  providence  punishes  nothing 
but  vices.  Therefore  human  law  rightly  allows  some  vices, 
by  not  repressing  them. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A  A.  i,  2),  law  is 
framed  as  a  rule  or  measure  of  human  acts.  Now  a  measure 
should  be  homogeneous  with  that  which  it  measures,  as 
stated  in  Metaph.  x.,  since  different  things  are  measured 
by  different  measures.  Wherefore  laws  imposed  on  men 
should  also  be  in  keeping  with  their  condition,  for,  as  Isidore 
says  (Etym.  ii.),  law  should  be  possible  both  according  to 
nature,  and  according  to  the  customs  of  the  country.  Now 
possibility  or  faculty  of  action  is  due  to  an  interior  habit  or 
disposition :  since  the  same  thing  is  not  possible  to  one  who 
has  not  a  virtuous  habit,  as  is  possible  to  one  who  has. 
Thus  the  same  is  not  possible  to  a  child  as  to  a  full-grown 
man:  for  which  reason  the  law  for  children  is  not  the  same 
as  for  adults,  since  many  things  are  permitted  to  children, 
which  in  an  adult  are  punished  by  law  or  at  any  rate  are 
open  to  blame.  In  like  manner  many  things  are  permissible 
to  men  not  perfect  in  virtue,  which  would  be  intolerable  in  a 
virtuous  man. 

Now  human  law  is  framed  for  a  number  of  human  beings, 
the  majority  of  whom  are  not  perfect  in  virtue.  Wherefore 
human  laws  do  not  forbid  all  vices,  from  which  the  virtuous 
abstain,  but  only  the  more  grievous  vices,  from  which  it 
is  possible  for  the  majority  to  abstain;  and  chiefly  those 
/  that  are  to  the  hurt  of  others,  without  the  prohibition  of 
=  which  human  society  could  not  be  maintained :  thus  human 
law  prohibits  murder,  theft  and  suchlike. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Audacity  seems  to  refer  to  the  assailing  of 
others.  Consequently  it  belongs  to  those  sins  chiefly 
whereby  one's  neighbour  is  injured:  and  these  sins  are  for- 
bidden by  human  law,  as  stated. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  purpose  of  human  law  is  to  lead  men  to 
virtue,  not  suddenly,  but  gradually.  Wherefore  it  does  not 
lay  upon  the  multitude  of  imperfect  men  the  burdens  of 
those   who   are   already   virtuous,   viz.,   that   they  should 


6;  THE  POWER  OF  HUMAN  LAW     Q.  96.  Art.  2 

abstain  from  all  evil.  Otherwise  these  imperfect  ones,  being 
unable  to  bear  such  precepts,  would  break  out  into  yet 
greater  evils:  thus  it  is  written  (Prov.  xxx.  33):  He  that 
violently  hloweth  his  nose,  hringeth  out  blood  ;  and  (Matth. 
ix.  17)  that  if  new  wine,  i.e.,  precepts  of  a  perfect  life,  is  put 
into  old  bottles,  i.e.,  into  imperfect  men,  the  bottles  break,  and 
the  wine  runneth  out,  i.e.,  the  precepts  are  despised,  and 
those  men,  from  contempt,  break  out  into  evils  worse  still. 
Reply  Obj.  3.  The  natural  law  is  a  participation  in  us  of 
the  eternal  law:  while  human  law  falls  short  of  the  eternal 
law.  Now  Augustine  says  {De  Lib.  Arb.  i.) :  The  law  which 
is  framed  for  the  government  of  states,  allows  and  leaves  un- 
punished many  things  that  are  punished  by  Divine  providence. 
Nor,  if  this  law  does  not  attempt  to  do  everything,  is  this  a 
reason  why  it  should  be  blamed  for  what  it  does.  Wherefore, 
too,  human  law  does  not  prohibit  everything  that  is  forbidden 
by  the  natural  law. 

Third  Article. 


i 


WHETHER   HUMAN   LAW  PRESCRIBES  ACTS  OF  ALL  THE 

VIRTUES  ? 


We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  human  law  does  not  prescribe 
acts  of  all  the  virtues.  For  vicious  acts  are  contrary  to  acts 
of  virtue.  But  human  law  does  not  prohibit  all  vices,  as 
stated  above  (A.  2).  Therefore  neither  does  it  prescribe  all 
acts  of  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  a  virtuous  act  proceeds  from  a  virtue. 
But  virtue  is  the  end  of  law;  so  that  whatever  is  from  a 
virtue,  cannot  come  under  a  precept  of  law.  Therefore 
human  law  does  not  prescribe  all  acts  of  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  law  is  ordained  to  the  common  good,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2).  But  some  acts  of  virtue  are 
ordained,  not  to  the  common  good,  but  to  private  good. 
Therefore  the  law  does  not  prescribe  all  acts  of  virtue. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  v.)  that  the 
law  prescribes  the  performance  of  the  acts  of  a  brave  man,  .  .  . 
and  the  acts  of  the  temperate  man,  .  .  .  and  the  acts  of  the  meek 


Q.  96.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  68 

man  :  and  in  like  manner  as  regards  the  other  virtues  and 
vices,  prescribing  the  former,  forbidding  the  latter. 

I  answer  that,  The  species  of  virtues  are  distinguished 
by  their  objects,  as  explained  above  (Q.  LIV.,  A.  2;  Q.  LX., 
A.  i;  Q.  LXII.,  A.  2).  Now  all  the  objects  of  virtues  can 
be  referred  either  to  the  private  good  of  an  individual,  or 
to  the  common  good  of  the  multitude :  thus  matters  of  forti- 
tude may  be  achieved  either  for  the  safety  of  the  state,  or 
for  upholding  the  rights  of  a  friend,  and  in  like  manner  with 
the  other  virtues.  But  law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2) 
is  ordained  to  the  common  good.  Wherefore  there  is  no 
virtue  whose  acts  cannot  be  prescribed  by  the  law.  Never- 
theless human  law  does  not  prescribe  concerning  all  the 
acts  of  every  virtue:  but  only  in  regard  to  those  that  are 
ordainable  to  the  common  good, — either  immediately,  as 
when  certain  things  are  done  directly  for  the  common  good, — 
or  mediately,  as  when  a  lawgiver  prescribes  certain  things 
pertaining  to  good  order,  whereby  the  citizens  are  directed 
in  the  upholding  of  the  common  good  of  justice  and  peace. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Human  law  does  not  forbid  all  vicious  acts, 
by  the  obligation  of  a  precept,  as  neither  does  it  prescribe 
all  acts  of  virtue.  But  it  forbids  certain  acts  of  each  vice, 
just  as  it  prescribes  some  acts  of  each  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  An  act  is  said  to  be  an  act  of  virtue  in  two 
ways.  First,  from  the  fact  that  a  man  does  something 
virtuous;  thus  the  act  of  justice  is  to  do  what  is  right,  and 
an  act  of  fortitude  is  to  do  brave  things :  and  in  this  way  law 
prescribes  certain  acts  of  virtue. — Secondly  an  act  of  virtue 
is  when  a  man  does  a  virtuous  thing  in  a  way  in  which  a 
virtuous  man  does  it.  Such  an  act  always  proceeds  from 
virtue :  and  it  does  not  come  under  a  precept  of  law,  but  is 
the  end  at  which  every  lawgiver  aims. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  There  is  no  virtue  whose  act  is  not  ordain- 
able to  the  common  good,  as  stated  above,  either  mediately 
or  immediately. 


69  THE  1\)\VER  OF  HUMAN  LAW     Q.  96.  Art.  4 


X 


Fourth  Article, 
whether  human  law  binds  a  man  in  conscience  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  human  law  does  not  bind  a  man 
in  conscience.  For  an  inferior  power  has  no  jurisdiction  in 
a  court  of  higher  power.  But  the  power  of  man,  which 
frames  human  law,  is  beneath  the  Divine  power.  Therefore 
human  law  cannot  impose  its  precept  in  a  Divine  court, 
such  as  is  the  court  of  conscience. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  judgment  of  conscience  depends 
chiefly  on  the  commandments  of  God.  But  sometimes 
God's  commandments  are  made  void  by  human  laws,  ac- 
cording to  Matth.  XV.  6:  You  have  made  void  the  command- 
ment of  God  for  your  tradition.  Therefore  human  law  does 
not  bind  a  man  in  conscience. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  human  laws  often  bring  loss  of  character 
and  injury  on  man,  according  to  Isa.  x.  i  et  seq.  :  Woe  to 
them  that  make  wicked  laws,  and  when  they  write,  write  in- 
justice ;  to  oppress  the  poor  in  judgment,  and  do  violence  to  the 
cause  of  the  humble  of  My  people.  But  it  is  lawful  for  anyone 
to  avoid  oppression  and  violence.  Therefore  human  laws  do 
not  bind  man  in  conscience. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  (i  Pet.  ii.  19) :  This  is  thanks- 
worthy,  if  for  conscience  .  .  .  a  man  endure  sorrows,  suffering 
wrongfully. 

I  answer  that,  Laws  framed  by  man  are  either  just  or  unjust. 
If  they  be  just,  they  have  the  power  of  binding  in  conscience, 
from  the  eternal  law  whence  they  are  derived,  according  to 
Prov.  viii.  15:  By  Me  kings  reign,  and  lawgivers  decree  just 
things.  Now  laws  are  said  to  be  just,  both  from  the  end, 
when,  to  wit,  they  are  ordained  to  the  common  good, — and 
from  their  author,  that  is  to  say,  when  the  law  that  is  made 
does  not  exceed  the  power  of  the  lawgiver, — and  from  their 
form,  when,  to  wit,  burdens  are  laid  on  the  subjects,  accord- 
ing to  an  equality  of  proportion  and  with  a  view  to  the 
common  good.     For,  since  one  man  is  a  part  of  the  com- 


u 


Q.  96.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  70 

munity,  each  man,  in  all  that  he  is  and  has,  belongs  to  the 
community;  just  as  a  part,  in  all  that  it  is,  belongs  to  the 
whole ;  wherefore  nature  inflicts  a  loss  on  the  part,  in  order 
to  save  the  whole:  so  that  on  this  account,  such  laws  as 
these,  which  impose  proportionate  burdens,  are  just  and 
binding  in  conscience,  and  are  legal  laws. 

On  the  other  hand  laws  may  be  unjust  in  two  ways:  first, 
by  being  contrary  to  human  good,  through  being  opposed 
to  the  things  mentioned  above: — either  in  respect  of  the  end, 
as  when  an  authority  imposes  on  his  subjects  burdensome 
laws,  conducive,  not  to  the  common  good,  but  rather  to  his 
own  cupidity  or  vainglory; — or  in  respect  of  the  author,  as 
when  a  man  makes  a  law  that  goes  beyond  the  power  com- 
mitted to  him; — or  in  respect  of  the  form,  as  when  burdens 
are  imposed  unequally  on  the  community,  although  with  a 
view  to  the  common  good.  The  like  are  acts  of  violence 
rather  than  laws;  because,  as  Augustine  says  {De  Lib.  Arh.  i.), 
a  law  that  is  not  just,  seems  to  he  no  law  at  all.  Wherefore 
such  laws  do  not  bind  in  conscience,  except  perhaps  in 
order  to  avoid  scandal  or  disturbance,  for  which  cause  a 
man  should  even  yield  his  right,  according  to  Matth.  v.  40, 
41:  If  a  man  .  .  .  take  away  thy  coat,  let  go  thy  cloak  also  unto 
him  ;  and  whosoever  will  force  thee  one  mile,  go  with  him  other 
two. 

Secondly,  laws  may  be  unjust  through  being  opposed  to 
the  Divine  good:  such  are  the  laws  of  tyrants  inducing  to 
idolatry,  or  to  anything  else  contrary  to  the  Divine  law: 
and  laws  of  this  kind  must  nowise  be  observed,  because,  as 
stated  in  Acts  v.  29,  we  ought  to  obey  God  rather  than  men. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  xiii.  i,  2),  all 
human  power  is  from  God  .  .  .  therefore  he  that  resisteth 
the  power,  in  matters  that  are  within  its  scope,  resisteth  the 
ordinance  of  God  ;  so  that  he  becomes  guilty  according  to 
his  conscience. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  This  argument  is  true  of  laws  that  are  con- 
trary to  the  commandments  of  God,  and  which  go  beyond 
the  scope  of  (human)  power.  Wherefore  in  such  matters 
human  law  should  not  be  obeyed. 


71  THE  POWER  OF  HUMAN  LAW     q.  96.  Art.  5 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  argument  is  true  of  a  law  that  inflicts 
unjust  hurt  on  its  subjects.  The  power  that  man  holds  from 
God  does  not  extend  to  this:  wherefore  neither  in  such 
matters  is  man  bound  to  obey  the  law,  provided  he  avoid 
giving  scandal  or  inflicting  a  more  grievous  hurt. 


Fifth  Article, 
whether  all  are  subject  to  the  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  not  all  are  subject  to  the  law. 
For  those  alone  are  subject  to  a  law  for  whom  a  law  is 
made.  But  the  Apostle  says  (i  Tim.  i.  9) :  The  law  is  not 
made  for  the  just  man.  Therefore  the  just  are  not  subject  to 
the  law. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Pope  Urban  says  [Decret.  xix.) :  He  that  is 
guided  by  a  private  law  need  not  for  any  reason  be  bound  by 
the  public  law.  Now  all  spiritual  men  are  led  by  the  private 
law  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  for  they  are  the  sons  of  God,  of 
whom  it  is  said  (Rom.  viii.  14) :  Whosoever  are  led  by  the 
Spirit  of  God,  they  are  the  sons  of  God.  Therefore  not  all 
men  are  subject  to  human  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Jurist  says  {Pandect.  Justin,  i.)  that 
the  sovereign  is  exempt  from  the  laws.  But  he  that  is  exempt 
from  the  law  is  not  bound  thereby.  Therefore  not  all  are 
subject  to  the  law. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  xiii.  i) :  Let  every 
soul  be  subject  to  the  higher  powers.  But  subjection  to  a 
power  seems  to  imply  subjection  to  the  laws  framed  by  that 
power.  Therefore  all  men  should  be  subject  to  human  law. 
/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  AA.  i,  2;  A.  3 
ad  2),  the  notion  of  law  contains  two  things;  first,  that  it  is 
a  rule  of  human  acts;  secondly,  that  it  has  coercive  power. 
Wherefore  a  man  may  be  subject  to  law  in  two  ways.  First, 
as  the  regulated  is  subject  to  the  regulator :  and,  in  this  way, 
whoever  is  subject  to  a  power,  is  subject  to  the  law  framed 
by  that  power.  But  it  may  happen  in  two  ways  that  one 
is  not  subject  to  a  power.     In  one  way,  by  being  altogether 


g.  96.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  72 

free  from  its  authority:  hence  the  subjects  of  one  city  or 
kingdom  are  not  bound  by  the  laws  of  the  sovereign  of 
another  city  or  kingdom,  since  they  are  not  subject  to  his 
authority.  In  another  way,  by  being  under  a  yet  higher 
law;  thus  the  subject  of  a  proconsul  should  be  ruled  by  his 
command,  but  not  in  those  matters  in  which  the  subject 
receives  his  orders  from  the  emperor :  for  in  these  matters,  he 
is  not  bound  by  the  mandate  of  the  lower  authority,  since 
he  is  directed  by  that  of  a  higher.  In  this  way,  one  who  is 
simply  subject  to  a  law,  may  not  be  subject  thereto  in  cer- 
tain matters,  in  respect  of  which  he  is  ruled  by  a  higher  law. 

Secondly,  a  man  is  said  to  be  subject  to  a  law  as  the 
coerced  is  subject  to  the  coercer.  In  this  way  the  virtuous 
and  righteous  are  not  subject  to  the  law,  but  only  the 
wicked.  Because  coercion  and  violence  are  contrary  to  the 
will :  but  the  will  of  the  good  is  in  harmony  with  the  law, 
whereas  the  will  of  the  wicked  is  discordant  from  it.  Where- 
fore in  this  sense  the  good  are  not  subject  to  the  law,  but 
only  the  wicked. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  argument  is  true  of  subjection  by  way 
of  coercion :  for,  in  this  way,  the  law  is  not  made  for  the  just 
men  :  because  they  are  a  law  to  themselves,  since  they  shew 
the  work  of  the  law  written  in  their  hearts,  as  the  Apostle  says 
(Rom.  ii.  14,  15).  Consequently  the  law  does  not  enforce 
itself  upon  them  as  it  does  on  the  wicked. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  law  of  the  Holy  Ghost  is  above  all  lav/ 
framed  by  man:  and  therefore  spiritual  men,  in  so  far  as 
they  are  led  by  the  law  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  are  not  subject 
to  the  law  in  those  matters  that  are  inconsistent  with  the 
guidance  of  the  Holy  Ghost.  Nevertheless  the  very  fact  that 
spiritual  men  are  subject  to  law,  is  due  to  the  leading  of  the 
Holy  Ghost,  according  to  i  Pet.  ii.  13:  Be  ye  subject  .  .  . 
to  every  human  creature  for  God^s  sake. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  sovereign  is  said  to  be  exempt  from  the 
laiv,  as  to  its  coercive  power;  since,  properly  speaking,  no 
man  is  coerced  by  himself,  and  Taw  has  no  coercive  power 
save  from  the  authority  of  the  sovereign.  Thus  then  is  the 
sovereign  said  to  be  exempt  from  the  law,  because  none  is 


73  THE  POWER  OF  HUMAN  LAW     Q.  96.  Art.  5 

competent  to  pass  sentence  on  him,  if  he  acts  against  the 
law.  ^Wherefore  on  Ps.  L.  6:  To  Thee  only  have  I  sinned,  a 
gloss  says  that  there,  is  no  man  who  can  judge  the  deeds  of  a 
king. — But  as  to  the  directive  force  of  law,  the  sovereign  is 
subject  to  the  law  by  his  own  will,  according  to  the  state- 
ment (Extra,  De  Constit.  cap.  cum  omnes)  that  whatever  law 
a  man  makes  for  another,  he  should  keep  himself.  And  a  wise 
authority  says  :  '  Obey  the  law  that  thou  makest  thyself.^ 
Moreover  the  Lord  reproaches  those  who  say  and  do  not  ; 
and  who  hind  heavy  burdens  and  lay  them  on  men^s  shoulders, 
but  with  a  finger  of  their  own  they  will  not  move  them  (Matth. 
xxiii.  3,  4).  Hence,  in  the  judgment  of  God,  the  sovereign 
is  not  exempt  from  the  law,  as  to  its  directive  force ;  but  he 
should  fulfil  it  of  his  own  free-will  and  not  of  constraint. — 
Again  the  sovereign  is  above  the  law,  in  so  far  as,  when  it  is 
expedient,  he  can  change  the  law,  and  dispense  in  it  accord- 
ing to  time  and  place. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  he  who  is  under  a  law  may  act  beside  the 

letter  of  the  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  he  who  is  subject  to  a  law  may 
not  act  beside  the  letter  of  the  law.  For  Augustine  says 
{De  Vera  Relig.  xxxi.) :  Although  men  judge  about  temporal 
laws  when  they  make  them,  yet  when  once  they  are  made  they 
must  pass  judgment  not  on  them,  but  according  to  them.  But 
if  anyone  disregard  the  letter  of  the  law,  saying  that  he 
observes  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver,  he  seems  to  pass 
judgment  on  the  law.  Therefore  it  is  not  right  for  one  who 
is  under  a  law  to  disregard  the  letter  of  the  law,  in  order  to 
observe  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  he  alone  is  competent  to  interpret  the 
law  who  can  make  the  law.  But  those  who  are  subject  to 
the  law  cannot  make  the  law.  Therefore  they  have  no 
right  to  interpret  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver,  but  should 
always  act  according  to  the  letter  of  the  law. 


\ 


Q.  96.  Art.  6     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  74 

Obj.  3.  Further,  every  wise  man  knows  how  to  explain 
his  intention  by  words.  But  those  who  framed  the  laws 
should  be  reckoned  wise:  for  Wisdom  says  (Prov.  viii.  15): 
By  Me  kings  reign,  and  lawgivers  decree  just  things.  There- 
fore we  should  not  judge  of  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver 
otherwise  than  b}^  the  words  of  the  law. 

On  the  contrary,  Hilary  says  [De  Trin.  iv.) :  The  meaning  of 
what  is  said  is  according  to  the  motive  for  saying  it  :  because 
things  are  not  subject  to  speech,  but  speech  to  things.  There- 
fore we  should  take  account  of  the  motive  of  the  lawgiver, 
rather  than  to  his  very  words. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  4) ,  every  law  is  directed 
to  the  common  weal  of  men,  and  derives  the  force  and 
nature  of  law  accordingly.  Hence  the  Jurist  says  [Pandect. 
Justin,  i.) :  By  no  reason  of  law,  or  favour  of  equity,  is  it  allow- 
able for  us  to  interpret  harshly,  and  render  burdensome,  those 
useful  measures  which  have  been  enacted  for  the  welfare  of  man. 
Now  it  happens  often  that  the  observance  of  some  point  of 
law  conduces  to  the  common  weal  in  the  majority  of  in- 
stances, and  yet,  in  some  cases,  is  very  hurtful.  Since  then 
the  lawgiver  cannot  have  in  view  every  single  case,  he 
shapes  the  law  according  to  what  happens  most  frequently, 
by  directing  his  attention  to  the  common  good.  Wherefore 
if  a  case  arise  wherein  the  observance  of  that  law  would  be 
hurtful  to  the  general  welfare,  it  should  not  be  observed. 
For  instance,  suppose  that  in  a  besieged  city  it  be  an  estab- 
lished law  that  the  gates  of  the  city  are  to  be  kept  closed, 
this  is  good  for  public  welfare  as  a  general  rule:  but,  if  it 
were  to  happen  that  the  enemy  are  in  pursuit  of  certain 
citizens,  who  are  defenders  of  the  city,  it  would  be  a  great 
loss  to  the  city,  if  the  gates  were  not  opened  to  them:  and 
so  in  that  case  the  gates  ought  to  be  opened,  contrary  to 
the  letter  of  the  law,  in  order  to  maintain  the  common  weal, 
which  the  lawgiver  had  in  view. 

Nevertheless  it  must  be  noted,  that  if  the  observance  of 
the  law  according  to  the  letter  does  not  involve  any  sudden 
risk  needing  instant  remedy,  it  is  not  competent  for  everyone 
to  expound  what  is  useful  and  what  is  not  useful  to  the 


75  THE  P0\\1':K  OF  HUMAN  LAW     Q.  96.  Art.  6 

state :  those  alone  can  do  this  who  are  in  authority,  and  who, 
on  account  of  suchhkc  cases,  have  the  power  to  dispense 
from  the  laws.  If,  however,  the  peril  be  so  sudden  as  not 
to  allow  of  the  delay  involved  by  referring  the  matter  to 
authority,  the  mere  necessity  brings  with  it  a  dispensation, 
since  necessity  knows  no  law. 

Reply  Ohj.  I.  He  who  in  a  case  of  necessity  acts  beside  the 
letter  of  the  law,  does  not  judge  of  the  law;  but  of  a  particu- 
lar case  in  which  he  sees  that  the  letter  of  the  law  is  not  to 
be  observed. 

Re-ply  Ohj.  2.  He  who  follows  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver, 
does  not  interpret  the  law  simply;  but  in  a  case  in  which  it 
is  evident,  by  reason  of  the  manifest  harm,  that  the  lawgiver 
intended  otherwise.  For  if  it  be  a  matter  of  doubt,  he  must 
either  act  according  to  the  letter  of  the  law,  or  consult  those 
in  power. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  No  man  is  so  wise  as  to  be  able  to  take 
account  of  every  single  case;  wherefore  he  is  not  able  suffi- 
ciently to  express  in  words  all  those  things  that  are  suit- 
able for  the  end  he  has  in  view.  And  even  if  a  lawgiver 
were  able  to  take  all  the  cases  into  consideration,  he  ought 
not  to  mention  them  all,  in  order  to  avoid  confusion:  but 
should  frame  the  law  according  to  that  which  is  of  most 
common  occurrence. 


QUESTION  XCVII. 

OF    CHANGE    IN    LAWS. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  change  in  laws:  under  which  head 
there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  human  law  is 
changeable  ?  (2)  Whether  it  should  be  always  changed, 
whenever  anything  better  occurs  ?  (3)  Whether  it  is 
abolished  by  custom,  and  whether  custom  obtains  the  force 
of  law  ?  (4)  Whether  the  application  of  human  law  should 
be  changed  by  dispensation  of  those  in  authority  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  human  law  should  be  changed  in  any  way  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  human  law  should  not  be 
changed  in  any  way  at  all.  Because  human  law  is  derived 
from  the  natural  law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCV.,  A.  2).  But 
the  natural  law  endures  unchangeably.  Therefore  human 
law  should  also  remain  without  any  change. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  as  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  v.),  a 
measure  should  be  absolutely  stable.  But  human  law  is 
the  measure  of  human  acts,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC, 
AA.  I,  2).     Therefore  it  should  remain  without  change. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  it  is  of  the  essence  of  law  to  be  just  and 
right,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCV.,  A.  2).  But  that  which  is 
right  once  is  right  always.  Therefore  that  which  is  law 
once,  should  be  always  law. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Lib.  Arb.  i.) :  A  tem- 
poral law,  however  just,  may  be  justly  changed  in  course  of  time. 

76 


^^  CHANGE  IN  LAWS  Q.  97.  Art.  i 

1  answer  thai,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XCI.,  A.  3),  human  law 
is  a  dictate  of  reason,  whereby  human  acts  are  directed. 
Thus  there  may  be  two  causes  for  the  just  change  of  human 
law :  one  on  the  part  of  reason ;  the  other  on  the  part  of  man 
whose  acts  are  regulated  by  law.  The  cause  on  the  part  of 
reason  is  that  it  seems  natural  to  human  reason  to  advance 
gradually  from  the  imperfect  to  the  perfect.  Hence,  in 
speculative  sciences,  we  see  that  the  teaching  of  the  early 
philosophers  was  imperfect,  and  that  it  was  afterwards  per- 
fected by  those  who  succeeded  them.  So  also  in  practical 
matters:  for  those  who  first  endeavoured  to  discover  some- 
thing useful  for  the  human  community,  not  being  able  by 
themselves  to  take  everything  into  consideration,  set  up 
certain  institutions  which  were  deficient  in  many  ways;  and 
these  were  changed  by  subsequent  lawgivers  who  made 
institutions  that  might  prove  less  frequently  deficient  in 
respect  of  the  common  weal.^"^—-^  ^ 

On  the  part  of  man,  whose  acts  are  regulated  by  law,  the 
law  can  be  rightly  changed  on  account  of  the  changed  con- 
dition of  man,  to  whom  different  things  are  expedient  accord- 
ing to  the  difference  of  his  condition.  An  example  is  pro- 
posed by  Augustine  {JDe  Lib.  Arb.  i.) :  If  the  people  have  a 
sense  of  moderation  and  responsibility ,  and  are  most  careful 
guardians  oj  the  common  weal,  it  is  right  to  enact  a  law  allow- 
ing such  a  people  to  choose  their  own  magistrates  for  the 
government  of  the  commonwealth.  But  if,  as  time  goes  on, 
the  same  people  become  so  corrupt  as  to  sell  their  votes, 
and  entrust  the  government  to  scoundrels  and  criminals  ;  then 
the  right  of  appointing  their  public  officials  is  rightly 
forfeit  to  such  a  people,  and  the  choice  devolves  to  a  few 
good  men. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  natural  law  is  a  participation  of  the 
eternal  law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCI.,  A.  2),  and  therefore 
endures  without  change,  owing  to  the  unchangeabJeness  and 
perfection  of  the  Divine  Reason,  the  Author  of  nature.  But 
the  reason  of  man  is  changeable  and  imperfect:  wherefore 
his  law  is  subject  to  change. — Moreover  the  natural  law 
contains  certain  universal  precepts,  which  are  everlasting: 


Q.  97.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGTCA  "  78 

whereas  human  law  contains  certain  particular  precepts, 
according  to  various  emergencies. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  measure  should  be  as  enduring  as  possible. 
But  nothing  can  be  absolutely  unchangeable  in  things  that 
are  subject  to  change.  And  therefore  human  law  cannot  be 
altogether  unchangeable. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  In  corporal  things,  right  is  predicated  abso- 
lutely: and  therefore,  as  far  as  itself  is  concerned,  always 
remains  right.  But  right  is  predicated  of  law  with  reference 
to  the  common  weal,  to  which  one  and  the  same  thing  is  not 
always  adapted,  as  stated  above:  wherefore  rectitude  of 
this  kind  is  subject  to  change. 

Second  Article. 

whether  human  law  should  always  be  changed, 
whenever  something  better  occurs  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  human  law  should  be  changed, 
whenever  something  better  occurs.  Because  human  laws 
are  devised  by  human  reason,  like  other  arts.  But  in  the 
other  arts,  the  tenets  of  former  times  give  place  to  others, 
if  something  better  occurs.  Therefore  the  same  should 
apply  to  human  laws. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  by  taking  note  of  the  past  we  can  provide 
for  the  future.  Now  unless  human  laws  had  been  changed 
when  it  was  found  possible  to  improve  them,  considerable 
inconvenience  would  have  ensued;  because  the  laws  of  old 
were  crude  in  many  points.  Therefore  it  seems  that  laws 
should  be  changed,  whenever  anything  better  occurs  to  be 
enacted. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  human  laws  are  enacted  about  single  acts 
of  man.  But  we  cannot  acquire  perfect  knowledge  in  sin- 
gular matters,  except  by  experience,  which  requires  time,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  ii.  Therefore  it  seems  that  as  time  goes  on 
it  is  possible  for  something  better  to  occur  for  legislation. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  stated  in  the  Decretals  {Dist.  xii.) : 
It  is  ahsurd,  and  a  detestahle  shame,  that  we  should  suffer  those 


79  CHANGE  IN  LAWS  Q.  97.  Art.  2 

traditions  to   he  chafiged  which    xvc    have  received  from  the 
fathers  of  old. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  human  law  is  rightly 
changed,  in  so  far  as  such  change  is  conducive  to  the  common 
weal.  But,  to  a  certain  extent,  the  mere  change  of  law  is 
of  itself  prejudicial  to  the  common  good:  because  custom 
avails  much  for  the  observance  of  laws,  seeing  that  what  is 
done  contrary  to  general  custom,  even  in  slight  matters, 
is  looked  upon  as  grave.  Consequently,  when  a  law  is 
changed,  the  binding  power  of  the  law  is  diminished,  in  so 
far  as  custom  is  abolished.  Wherefore  human  law  should 
never  be  changed,  unless,  in  some  way  or  other,  the  common 
weal  be  compensated  according  to  the  extent  of  the  harm 
done  in  this  respect.  Such  compensation  may  arise  either 
from  some  very  great  and  very  evident  benefit  conferred  by 
the  new  enactment;  or  from  the  extreme  urgency  of  the 
case,  due  to  the  fact  that  either  the  existing  law  is  clearly 
unjust,  or  its  observance  extremely  harmful.  Wherefore 
the  Jurist  says  [Pandect.  Justin,  i.)  that  in  establishing  new 
laws,  there  should  he  evidence  of  the  henefit  to  be  derived,  before 
departing  from  a  law  which  has  long  been  considered  just. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Rules  of  art  derive  their  force  from  reason 
alone:  and  therefore  whenever  something  better  occurs,  the 
rule  followed  hitherto  should  be  changed.  But  laws  derive 
very  great  force  from  custom,  as  the  Philosopher  states 
[Polit.  ii.) :  consequently  they  should  not  be  quickly  changed. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  argument  proves  that  laws  ought  to 
be  changed:  not  in  view  of  any  improvement,  but  for  the 
sake  of  a  great  benefit  or  in  a  case  of  great  urgency,  as  stated 
above.     This  answer  applies  also  to  the  Third  Objection. 

Third  Article, 
whether  custom  can  obtain  force  of  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  custom  cannot  obtain  force  of 
law,  nor  abolish  a  law.  Because  human  law  is  derived 
from  the  natural  law  and  from  the  Divine  law,  as  stated 


Q.  97.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  80 

above  (Q.  XCIII.,  A.  3;  Q.  XCV.,  A.  2).  But  human  custom 
cannot  change  either  the  law  of  nature  or  the  Divine  law. 
Therefore  neither  can  it  change  human  law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  many  evils  cannot  make  one  good.  But 
he  who  first  acted  against  the  law,  did  evil.  Therefore  by 
multiplying  such  acts,  nothing  good  is  the  result.  Now  a 
law  is  something  good;  since  it  is  a  rule  of  human  acts. 
Therefore  law  is  not  abolished  by  custom,  so  that  the  mere 
custom  should  obtain  force  of  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  framing  of  laws  belongs  to  those 
public  men  whose  business  it  is  to  govern  the  community; 
wherefore  private  individuals  cannot  make  laws.  But 
custom  grows  by  the  acts  of  private  individuals.  Therefore 
custom  cannot  obtain  force  of  law,  so  as  to  abolish  the  law. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Ep.  ad  Casulan.) :  The 
customs  of  God's  people  and  the  institutions  of  our  ancestors 
are  to  be  considered  as  laws.  And  those  who  throw  contempt 
on  the  customs  of  the  Church  ought  to  be  punished  as  those  who 
disobey  the  law  of  God. 

I  answer  that,  All  law  proceeds  from  the  reason  and  will 
of  the  lawgiver;  the  Divine  and  natural  laws  from  the 
reasonable  will  of  God;  the  human  law  from  the  will  of 
man,  regulated  by  reason.  Now  just  as  human  reason  and 
will,  in  practical  matters,  may  be  made  manifest  by  speech, 
so  may  they  be  made  known  by  deeds:  since  seemingly  a 
man  chooses  as  good  that  which  he  carries  into  execution. 
But  it  is  evident  that  by  human  speech,  law  can  be  both 
changed  and  expounded,  in  so  far  as  it  manifests  the  interior 
movement  and  thought  of  human  reason.  Wherefore  by 
actions  also,  especially  if  they  be  repeated,  so  as  to  make  a 
custom,  law  can  be  changed  and  expounded ;  and  also  some- 
thing can  be  established  which  obtains  force  of  law,  in  so  far 
as  by  repeated  external  actions,  the  inward  movement  of 
the  will,  and  concepts  of  reason  are  most  effectually  de- 
clared ;  for  when  a  thing  is  done  again  and  again,  it  seems  to 
proceed  from  a  deliberate  judgment  of  reason.  Accordingly, 
custom  has  the  force  of  a  law,  abolishes  law,  and  is  the  inter- 
preter of  law. 


8i  CHANGE  IN  LAWS  Q.  97.  Art.  3 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  natural  and  Divine  laws  proceed  from 
the  Divine  will,  as  stated  above.  Wherefore  they  cannot 
be  changed  by  a  custom  proceeding  from  the  will  of  man, 
but  only  by  Divine  authority.  Hence  it  is  that  no  custom 
can  prevail  over  the  Divine  or  natural  laws :  for  Isidore  says 
(Synon.  ii.) :  Let  custom  yield  to  authority  :  evil  customs  should 
be  eradicated  by  law  and  reason. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XCVL,  A.  6),  human 
laws  fail  in  some  cases :  wherefore  it  is  possible  sometimes  to 
act  beside  the  law;  namely,  in  a  case  where  the  law  fails; 
yet  the  act  will  not  be  evil.  And  when  such  cases  are 
multiplied,  by  reason  of  some  change  in  man,  then  custom 
shows  that  the  law  is  no  longer  useful:  just  as  it  might  be 
declared  by  the  verbal  promulgation  of  a  law  to  the  con- 
trary. If,  however,  the  same  reason  remains,  for  which 
the  law  was  useful  hitherto,  then  it  is  not  the  custom  that 
prevails  against  the  law,  but  the  law  that  overcomes  the 
custom:  unless  perhaps  the  sole  reason  for  the  law  seeming 
useless,  be  that  it  is  not  possible  according  to  the  custom  of  the 
country,  which  has  been  stated  to  be  one  of  the  conditions 
of  law.  For  it  is  not  easy  to  set  aside  the  custom  of  a  whole 
people. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  people  among  whom  a  custom  is  intro-  \ 
duced  may  be  of  two  conditions.  For  if  they  are  free,  and 
able  to  make  their  own  laws,  the  consent  of  the  whole  people 
expressed  by  a  custom  counts  far  more  in  favour  of  a  par- 
ticular observance,  than  does  the  authority  of  the  sovereign, 
who  has  not  the  power  to  frame  laws,  except  as  representing 
the  people.  Wherefore  although  each  individual  cannot 
make  laws,  yet  the  whole  people  can.  If  however  the  people 
have  not  the  free  power  to  make  their  own  laws,  or  to 
abohsh  a  law  made  by  a  higher  authority;  nevertheless 
with  such  a  people  a  prevailing  custom  obtains  force  of 
law,  in  so  far  as  it  is  tolerated  by  those  to  whom  it  belongs 
to  make  laws  for  that  people :  because  by  the  very  fact  that 
they  tolerate  it  they  seem  to  approve  of  that  which  is  intro- 
duced by  custom. 

11.3  6 


y.  97.  Akt.  4.     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  82 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  rulers  of  the  people  can  dispense  from 

human  laws  ? 

Wc  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  rulers  of  the  people  cannot 
dispense  from  human  laws.  For  the  law  is  established  for 
the  common  weal,  as  Isidore  says  [Etym.  ii.).  But  the 
common  good  should  not  be  set  aside  for  the  private  con- 
venience of  an  individual:  because,  as  the  Philosopher  says 
[Ethic,  i.),  the  good  of  the  nation  is  more  godlike  than  the  good 
of  one  man.  Therefore  it  seems  that  a  man  should  not  be 
dispensed  from  acting  in  compliance  with  the  general  law. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  those  who  are  placed  over  others  are 
commanded  as  follows  (Deut.  i.  17) :  You  shall  hear  the  little 
as  well  as  the  great ;  neither  shall  you  respect  any  man's  person, 
because  it  is  the  judgment  of  God.  But  to  allow  one  man  to 
do  that  which  is  equally  forbidden  to  all,  seems  to  be  respect 
of  persons.  Therefore  the  rulers  of  a  community  cannot 
grant  such  dispensations,  since  this  is  against  a  precept  of 
the  Divine  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  human  law,  in  order  to  be  just,  should 
accord  with  the  natural  and  Divine  laws :  else  it  would  not 
foster  religion,  nor  be  helpful  to  discipline,  which  is  requisite 
to  the  nature  of  law,  as  laid  down  by  Isidore  (Etym.  ii.). 
But  no  man  can  dispense  from  the  Divine  and  natural  laws. 
Neither,  therefore,  can  he  dispense  from  the  human  law. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  ix.  17) :  A  dis- 
pensation is  committed  to  me. 

I  answer  that.  Dispensation,  properly  speaking,  denotes  a 
measuring  out  to  individuals  of  some  common  goods:  thus 
the  head  of  a  household  is  called  a  dispenser,  because  to 
each  member  of  the  household  he  distributes  work  and 
necessaries  of  life  in  due  weight  and  measure.  Accordingly 
in  every  community  a  man  is  said  to  dispense,  from  the  very 
fact  that  he  directs  how  some  general  precept  is  to  be  ful- 
filled by  each  individual.  Now  it  happens  at  times  that  a 
percept,  which  is  conducive  to  the  common  weal  as  a  general 


83  CHANGE  IN  LAWS  Q.  97.  Art.  4 

rule,  is  not  good  for  a  particular  individual,  or  in  some  par- 
ticular case,  either  because  it  would  hinder  some  greater 
good,  or  because  it  would  be  the  occasion  of  some  evil,  as 
explained  above  (Q.  XCVL,  A.  6).  But  it  would  be  dan- 
gerous to  leave  this  to  the  discretion  of  each  individual, 
except  perhaps  by  reason  of  an  evident  and  sudden  emer- 
gency, as  stated  above  (ibid.).  Consequently  he  who  is 
placed  over  a  community  is  empowered  to  dispense  in  a 
human  law  that  rests  upon  his  authority,  so  that,  when  the 
law  fails  in  its  application  to  persons  or  circumstances,  he 
may  allow  the  precept  of  the  law  not  to  be  observed.  If 
however  he  grant  this  permission  without  any  such  reason, 
and  of  his  mere  will,  he  will  be  an  unfaithful  or  an  imprudent 
dispenser:  unfaithful,  if  he  has  not  the  common  good  in 
view;  imprudent,  if  he  ignores  the  reasons  for  granting  dis- 
pensations. Hence  Our  Lord  says  (Luke  xii.  42) :  Who, 
thinkest  thou,  is  the  faithful  and  wise  dispenser  (Douay, — 
steward) ,  whom  his  lord  setteth  over  his  family  ? 

Reply  Ob] .  1.  When  a  person  is  dispensed  from  observing 
the  general  law,  this  should  not  be  done  to  the  prejudice  of, 
but  with  the  intention  of  benefiting,  the  common  good. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  is  not  respect  of  persons  if  unequal 
measures  are  served  out  to  those  who  are  themselves  un- 
equal. Wherefore  when  the  condition  of  any  person  re- 
quires that  he  should  reasonably  receive  special  treatment,  it 
is  not  respect  of  persons  if  he  be  the  object  of  special  favour. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Natural  law,  so  far  as  it  contains  general 
precepts,  which  never  fail,  does  not  allow  of  dispensation. 
In  the  other  precepts,  however,  which  are  as  conclusions  of 
the  general  precepts,  man  sometimes  grants  a  dispensation: 
for  instance,  that  a  loan  should  not  be  paid  back  to 
the  betrayer  of  his  country,  or  something  similar.  But  to 
the  Divine  law  each  man  stands  as  a  private  person  to  the 
public  law  to  which  he  is  subject.  Wherefore  just  as  none 
can  dispense  from  public  human  law,  except  the  man  from 
whom  the  law  derives  its  authority,  or  his  delegate;  so,  in 
the  precepts  of  the  Divine  law,  which  are  from  God,  none 
can  dispense  but  God,  or  the  man  to  whom  He  may  give 
special  power  for  that  purpose. 


QUESTION    XCVIII. 

OF  THE  OLD  LAW. 

{In  Six  Articles.) 

In  due  sequence  we  must  now  consider  the  Old  Law;  and 
(i)  The  Law  itself:  (2)  its  precepts.  Under  the  first  head 
there  are  six  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  the  Old  Law 
was  good  ?  (2)  Whether  it  was  from  God  ?  (3)  Whether 
it  came  from  Him  through  the  angels  ?  (4)  Whether  it 
was  given  to  all  ?  (5)  Whether  it  was  binding  on  all  ? 
(6)  Whether  it  was  given  at  a  suitable  time  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  the  old  law  was  good  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  was  not  good. 
For  it  is  written  (Ezech.  xx.  25) :  /  gave  them  statutes  that 
were  not  good,  and  judgments  in  which  they  shall  not  live.  But 
a  law  is  not  said  to  be  good  except  on  account  of  the  goodness 
of  the  precepts  that  it  contains.  Therefore  the  Old  Law 
was  not  good. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  it  belongs  to  the  goodness  of  a  law  that 
it  conduce  to  the  common  welfare,  as  Isidore  says  [Etym.  ii.). 
But  the  Old  Law  was  not  salutary;  rather  was  it  deadly  and 
hurtful.  For  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  vii.  8,  seq.) :  Without 
the  law  sin  was  dead.  And  I  lived  some  time  without  the  law. 
But  when  the  commandment  came  sin  revived  ;  and  I  died. 
Again  he  says  (Rom.  v.  20) :  Law  entered  in  that  sin  might 
abound.    Therefore  the  Old  Law  was  not  good. 

84 


85  THE  OLD  LAW  q.  98.  Art.  i 

Obj.  3.  Further,  it  belongs  to  the  goodness  of  the  law  that 
it  should  be  possible  to  obey  it,  both  according  to  nature, 
and  according  to  human  custom.  But  such  the  Old  Law 
was  not:  since  Peter  said  (Acts  xv.  10) :  Why  tempt  you  (God) 
to  put  a  yoke  on  the  necks  of  the  disciples,  which  neither  our 
fathers  nor  we  have  been  able  to  bear  ?  Therefore  it  seems 
that  the  Old  Law  was  not  good. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  vii.  12) :  Where- 
fore the  law  indeed  is  holy,  and  the  commandment  holy,  and 
just,  and  good. 

I  answer  that.  Without  any  doubt,  the  Old  Law  was  good. 
For  just  as  a  doctrine  is  shown  to  be  good  by  the  fact  that  it 
accords  with  right  reason,  so  is  a  law  proved  to  be  good  if 
it  accords  with  reason.  Now  the  Old  Law  was  in  accordance 
with  reason.  Because  it  repressed  concupiscence  which  is 
in  conflict  with  reason,  as  evidenced  by  the  commandment, 
Thou  shall  not  covet  thy  neighbour'' s  goods  [Cf.  Exod.  xx.  17). 
Moreover  the  same  law  forbade  all  kinds  of  sin;  and  these 
too  are  contrary  to  reason.  Consequently  it  is  evident 
that  it  was  a  good  law.  The  Apostle  argues  in  the  same 
way  (Rom.  vii.) :  /  am  delighted,  says  he  [verse  22),  with  the 
law  of  God,  according  to  the  inward  man  :  and  again  (verse  16) : 
/  consent  to  the  law,  that  is  good. 

But  it  must  be  noted  that  the  good  has  various  degrees, 
as  Dionysius  states  [Div.  Nom.  iv.) :  for  there  is  a  perfect 
good,  and  an  imperfect  good.  In  things  ordained  to  an  end, 
there  is  perfect  goodness  when  a  thing  is  such  that  it  is 
sufficient  in  itself  to  conduce  to  the  end:  while  there  is  im- 
perfect goodness  when  a  thing  is  of  some  assistance  in  attain- 
ing the  end,  but  is  not  sufftcient  for  the  realization  thereof. 
Thus  a  medicine  is  perfectly  good,  if  it  gives  health  to  a 
man;  but  it  is  imperfect,  if  it  helps  to  cure  him,  without 
being  able  to  bring  him  back  to  health.  Again  it  must  be 
observed  that  the  end  of  human  law  is  different  from  the 
end  of  Divine  law.  For  the  end  of  human  law  is  the  tem- 
poral tranquillity  of  the  state,  which  end  law  effects  by 
directing  external  actions,  as  regards  those  evils  which 
might  disturb  the  peaceful  condition  of  the  state.     On  the 


Q.  98.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  86 

other  hand,  the  end  of  the  Divine  law  is  to  bring  man  to 
that  end  which  is  everlasting  happiness;  which  end  is  hin- 
dered by  any  sin,  not  only  of  external,  but  also  of  internal 
action.  Consequently  that  which  suffices  for  the  perfection 
of  human  law,  viz.,  the  prohibition  and  punishment  of  sin, 
does  not  suffice  for  the  perfection  of  the  Divine  law:  but  it 
is  requisite  that  it  should  make  man  altogether  fit  to  par- 
take of  everlasting  happiness.  Now  this  cannot  be  done 
save  by  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  whereby  charity,  which 
fulfilleth  the  law,  .  .  .  is  spread  abroad  in  our  hearts  (Rom. 
v.  5):  since  the  grace  of  God  is  life  everlasting  [ibid.  vi.  23). 
But  the  Old  Law  could  not  confer  this  grace,  for  this  was 
reserved  to  Christ;  because,  as  it  is  written  (John  i.  17),  the 
law  was  given  by  Moses,  grace  and  truth  came  by  Jesus 
Christ.  Consequently  the  Old  Law  was  good  indeed,  but 
imperfect,  according  to  Heb.  vii.  19 :  The  law  brought  nothing 
to  perfection. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  Lord  refers  there  to  the  ceremonial 
precepts;  which  are  said  not  to  be  good,  because  they  did 
not  confer  grace  unto  the  remission  of  sins,  although  by 
fulfilling  these  precepts  man  confessed  himself  a  sinner. 
Hence  it  is  said  pointedly,  and  judgments  in  which  they  shall 
not  live  ;  i.e.,  whereby  they  are  unable  to  obtain  life ;  and  so 
the  text  goes  on:  And  I  polluted  them,  i.e.,  showed  them  to 
be  polluted,  in  their  own  gifts,  when  they  offered  all  that 
opened  the  womb,  for  their  offences. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  law  is  said  to  have  been  deadly,  as 
being  not  the  cause,  but  the  occasion  of  death,  on  account 
of  its  imperfection:  in  so  far  as  it  did  not  confer  grace 
enabling  man  to  fulfil  what  it  prescribed,  and  to  avoid  what 
it  forbade.  Hence  this  occasion  was  not  given  to  men,  but 
taken  by  them.  Wherefore  the  Apostle  says  [ibid.  11): 
Sin,  taking  occasion  by  the  commandment,  seduced  me,  and 
by  it  killed  me.  In  the  same  sense  when  it  is  said  that  the 
law  entered  in  that  sin  might  abound,  the  conjunction  that 
must  be  taken  as  consecutive  arid  not  final:  in  so  far  as  men, 
taking  occasion  from  the  law,  sinned  all  the  more,  both 
because  a  sin  became  more  grievous  after  law  had  forbidden 


8;  THE  OLD  LAW  Q.  98.  Art.  2 

it,  and  because  concupiscence  increased,  since  we  desire  a 
thing  the  more  from  its  being  forbidden. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  yoke  of  the  law  could  not  be  borne 
without  the  help  of  grace,  which  the  law  did  not  confer:  for 
it  is  written  (Rom.  ix.  16) :  //  is  not  of  him  that  willeth,  nor  of 
him  that  runneth,  viz.,  that  he  wills  and  runs  in  the  com- 
mandments of  God,  hut  of  God  that  showeth  mercy.  Where- 
fore it  is  \vi'itten  (Ps.  cxviii.  32) :  /  have  run  the  way  of  Thy 
commandments,  when  Thou  didst  enlarge  my  heart,  i.e.,  by 
giving  me  grace  and  charity. 

Second  Article, 
whether  the  old  law  was  from  god  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  was  not  from  God. 
For  it  is  written  (Deut.  xxxii.  4) :  The  works  of  God  are  perfect. 
But  the  Law  was  imperfect,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  There- 
fore the  Old  Law  was  not  from  God. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  it  is  written  (Eccles.  iii.  14) :  /  have 
learned  that  all  the  works  which  God  hath  made  continue  for 
ever.  But  the  Old  Law  does  not  continue  for  ever:  since 
the  Apostle  says  (Heb.  vii.  18) :  There  is  indeed  a  setting  aside 
of  the  former  commandment,  because  of  the  weakness  and  un- 
profitableness thereof.  Therefore  the  Old  Law  was  not  from 
God. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  a  wise  lawgiver  should  remove,  not  only 
evil,  but  also  the  occasions  of  evil.  But  the  Old  Law  was 
an  occasion  of  sin,  as  stated  above  (A.  t  ad  2).  Therefore 
the  giving  of  such  a  law  does  not  appertain  to  God,  to  Whom 
none  is  like  among  the  lawgivers  (Job  xxxvi.  22). 

Obj.  4.  Further,  it  is  written  (i  Tim.  ii.  4)  that  God  will 
have  all  men  to  be  saved.  But  the  Old  Law  did  not  sufftce 
to  save  man,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  Therefore  the  giving 
of  such  a  law  did  not  appertain  to  God.  Therefore  the  Old 
Law  was  not  from  God. 

On  the  contrary.  Our  Lord  said  (Matth.  xv.  6)  while  speak- 
ing to  the  Jews,  to  whom  the  Law  was  given:  You  have 


Q.  98.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGTCA  "  88 

made  void  the  commandment  of  God  for  your  tradition.  And 
shortly  before  [verse  4)  He  had  said:  Honour  thy  father  and 
mother,  which  is  contained  expressly  in  the  Old  Law  (Exod. 
XX.  12;  Deut.  V.  16).     Therefore  the  Old  Law  was  from  God. 

/  answer  that,  The  Old  Law  was  given  by  the  good  God, 
Who  is  the  Father  of  Our  Lord  Jesus  Christ.  For  the  Old 
Law  ordained  men  to  Christ  in  two  ways.  First  by  bearing 
witness  to  Christ ;  wherefore  He  Himself  says  (Luke  xxiv.  44) : 
All  things  must  needs  he  fulfilled,  which  are  written  in  the 
law  .  .  .,  and  in  the  frophets,  and  in  the  psalms,  concerning 
Me  :  and  (John  v.  46) :  //  yoii  did  believe  Moses,  you  would 
perhaps  believe  Me  also  ;  for  he  wrote  of  Me. — Secondly,  as 
a  kind  of  disposition,  since  by  withdrawing  men  from  idola- 
trous worship,  it  enclosed  (concludebat)  them  in  the  worship 
of  one  God,  by  Whom  the  human  race  was  to  be  saved 
through  Christ.  Wherefore  the  Apostle  says  (Gal.  iii.  23) : 
Before  the  faith  came,  we  were  kept  under  the  law  shut  up 
[conclusi),  unto  that  faith  which  was  to  be  revealed.  Now  it  is 
evident  that  the  same  thing  it  is,  which  gives  a  disposition 
to  the  end,  and  which  brings  to  the  end;  and  when  I  say 
the  same,  I  mean  that  it  does  so  either  by  itself  or  through 
its  subjects.  For  the  devil  would  not  make  a  law  whereby 
men  would  be  led  to  Christ,  Who  was  to  cast  him  out,  ac- 
cording to  Matth.  xii.  26:  If  Satan  cast  out  Satan,  his  kingdom 
is  divided  (Vulg., — he  is  divided  against  himself).  Therefore 
the  Old  Law  was  given  by  the  same  God,  from  WTiom  came 
salvation  to  man,  through  the  grace  of  Christ. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Nothing  prevents  a  thing  being  not  perfect 
simply,  and  yet  perfect  in  respect  of  time:  thus  a  boy  is 
said  to  be  perfect,  not  simply,  but  with  regard  to  the  con- 
dition of  time.  So,  too,  precepts  that  are  given  to  children 
are  perfect  in  comparison  with  the  condition  of  those  to  whom 
they  are  given,  although  they  are  not  perfect  simply.  Hence 
the  Apostle  says  (Gal.  iii.  24) :  The  law  was  our  pedagogue  in 
Christ. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Those  works  of  God  endure  for  ever  which 
God  so  made  that  they  would  endure  for  ever;  and  these 
are  His  perfect  works.     But  the  Old  Law  was  set  aside  when 


89  THE  OLD  LAW  Q.  98.  Art.  2 

there  came  the  perfection  of  grace;  not  as  though  it  were 
evil,  but  as  being  weak  and  useless  for  this  time;  because, 
as  the  Apostle  goes  on  to  say,  the  law  brought  nothing  to 
perfection:  hence  he  says  (Gal.  iii.  25):  After  the  faith  is 
come,  we  are  no  longer  under  a  pedagogue. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  stated  above  (0.  LXXIX.,  A.  4),  God 
sometimes  permits  certain  ones  to  fall  into  sin,  that  they 
may  thereby  be  humbled.  So  also  did  He  wish  to  give  such 
a  law  as  men  by  their  own  forces  could  not  fulfil,  so  that, 
while  presuming  on  their  own  powers,  they  might  find 
themselves  to  be  sinners,  and  being  humbled  might  have 
recourse  to  the  help  of  grace. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  Although  the  Old  Law  did  not  suffice  to  save 
man,  yet  another  help  from  (lod  besides  the  Law  was  avail- 
able for  man,  viz.,  faith  in  the  Mediator,  by  which  the 
fathers  of  old  were  justified  even  as  we  are.  Accordingly 
God  did  not  fail  man  by  giving  him  insufficient  aids  to 
salvation. 

Third  Article, 
whether  the  old  law  was  given  through  the  angels  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  was  not  given 
through  the  angels,  but  immediately  by  God.  For  an  angel 
means  a  messenger  ;  so  that  the  word  angel  denotes  ministry, 
not  lordship,  according  to  Ps.  cii.  20,  21:  Bless  the  Lord  all 
ye  His  angels  .  .  .  you  ministers  of  His.  But  the  Old  Law 
is  related  to  have  been  given  by  the  Lord:  for  it  is  written 
(Exod.  XX.  i) :  And  the  Lord  spoke  .  .  .  these  words,  and 
further  on:  I  am  the  Lord  Thy  God.  Moreover  the  same 
expression  is  often  repeated  in  Exodus,  and  in  the  later 
books  of  the  Law.  Therefore  the  Law  was  given  by  God 
immediately. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  according  to  John  i.  17,  the  Law  zcas 
given  by  Moses.  But  Moses  received  it  from  God  immedi- 
ately: for  it  is  written  (Exod.  xxxiii.  11) :  The  Lord  spoke  to 
Moses  face  to  face,  as  a  man  is  wont  to  speak  to  his  friend. 
Therefore  the  Old  Law  was  given  by  God  immediately. 


Q.  98.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGTCA  "  90 

Obj.  3.  Further,  it  belongs  to  the  sovereign  alone  to  make 
a  law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  3).  But  God  alone  is 
Sovereign  as  regards  the  salvation  of  souls :  while  the  angels 
are  the  ministering  spirits,  as  stated  in  Heb.  i.  14.  Therefore 
it  was  not  meet  for  the  Law  to  be  given  through  the  angels, 
since  it  is  ordained  to  the  salvation  of  souls. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  said  (Gal,  iii.  19)  that  the 
Law  was  given  (Vulg., — ordained)  by  angels  in  the  hand  of  a 
Mediator.  And  Stephen  said  (Acts  vii.  53) :  [Who)  have 
received  the  Law  by  the  disposition  of  angels. 

I  answer  that.  The  Law  was  given  by  God  through  the 
angels.  And  besides  the  general  reason  given  by  Dionysius 
{Ccel.  Hier.  iv.),  viz.,  that  the  gifts  of  God  should  be  brought  to 
men  by  means  of  the  angels,  there  is  a  special  reason  why  the 
Old  Law  should  have  been  given  through  them.  For  it  has 
been  stated  (AA.  i,  2)  that  the  Old  Law  was  imperfect,  and 
yet  disposed  man  to  that  perfect  salvation  of  the  human 
race,  which  was  to  come  through  Christ.  Now  it  is  to  be 
observed  that  wherever  there  is  an  order  of  powers  or  arts, 
he  that  holds  the  highest  place,  himself  exercises  the  prin- 
cipal and  perfect  acts;  while  those  things  which  dispose  to 
the  ultimate  perfection  are  effected  by  him  through  his 
subordinates :  thus  the  ship-builder  himself  rivets  the  planks 
together,  but  prepares  the  material  by  means  of  the  work- 
men who  assist  him  under  his  direction.  Consequently  it 
was  fitting  that  the  perfect  law  of  the  New  Testament 
should  be  given  by  the  incarnate  God  immediately  ;  but 
that  the  Old  Law  should  be  given  to  men  by  the  ministers 
of  God,  i.e.,  by  the  angels.  It  is  thus  that  the  Apostle  at 
the  beginning  of  his  epistle  to  the  Hebrews  (i.  2)  proves  the 
excellence  of  the  New  Law  over  the  Old;  because  in  the  New 
Testament  God  .  .  .  hath  spoken  to  us  by  His  Son,  whereas 
in  the  Old  Testament  the  word  was  spoken  by  angels  (ii.  2). 

Reply  Obj.  i.  As  Gregory  says  at  the  beginning  of  his 
Morals  [PrcBf.,  chap,  i.),  the  angel  who  is  described  to  have 
appeared  to  Moses,  is  sometimes  mentioned  as  an  angel,  some- 
times as  the  Lord  :  an  angel,  in  truth,  in  respect  of  that  which 
was  subservient  to  the  external  delivery ;  and  the  Lord,  because 


91  THE  OLD  LAW  Q.  98.  Art.  3 

He  was  the  Director  within,  Who  supported  the  effectual  power 
of  speaking.  Hence  also  it  is  that  the  angel  spoke  as  per- 
sonating the  Lord. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  Augustine  says  (Gen.  ad  lit.  xii.),  it  is 
stated  in  Exodus  that  the  Lord  spoke  to  Moses  face  to  face  ; 
and  shortly  afterwards  we  read:  '  Show  me  Thy  glory.' 
Therejore  he  perceived  what  he  saw  and  he  desired  what  he  saw 
not.  Hence  he  did  not  see  the  very  Essence  of  God;  and 
consequently  he  was  not  taught  by  Him  immediately. 
Accordingly  when  Scripture  states  that  He  spoke  to  him  face 
to  face,  this  is  to  be  understood  as  expressing  the  opinion  of 
the  people,  who  thought  that  Moses  was  speaking  with  God 
mouth  to  mouth,  when  God  spoke  and  appeared  to  him,  by 
means  of  a  subordinate  creature,  i.e.,  an  angel  and  a  cloud. — 
Again  we  may  say  that  this  vision  face  to  face  means  some 
kind  of  sublime  and  familiar  contemplation,  inferior  to  the 
vision  of  the  Divine  Essence. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  It  is  for  the  sovereign  alone  to  make  a  law 
by  his  own  authority;  but  sometimes  after  making  a  law,  he 
promulgates  it  through  others.  Thus  God  made  the  Law 
by  His  own  authority,  but  He  promulgated  it  through  the 
angels. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  old  law  should  have  been  given  to  the 

jews  alone  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  should  not  have  been 
given  to  the  Jews  alone.  For  the  Old  Law  disposed  men  for 
the  salvation  which  was  to  come  through  Christ,  as  stated 
above  (A A.  2,  3).  But  that  salvation  was  to  come  not  to 
the  Jews  alone  but  to  all  nations,  according  to  Isa.  xlix.  6: 
It  is  a  small  thing  that  thou  shouldst  he  my  servant  to  raise 
up  the  tribes  of  Jacob,  and  to  convert  the  dregs  of  Israel. 
Behold  I  have  given  thee  to  he  the  light  of  the  Gentiles,  that  thou 
may  est  be  My  salvation,  even  to  the  farthest  part  of  the  earth. 
Therefore  the  Old  Law  should  have  been  given  to  all  nations, 
and  not  to  one  people  only. 


Q.  98.  Art.  4     THE  *'  SUMMA  TTTEOLOGTCA  "  92 

Obj.  2.  Further,  according  to  Acts  x.  34,  35,  God  is  not  a 
respecter  of  persons  :  but  in  every  nation,  he  that  feareth  Him, 
and  worketh  justice,  is  acceptable  to  Him.  Therefore  the 
way  of  salvation  should  not  have  been  opened  to  one  people 
more  than  to  another. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  law  was  given  through  the  angels,  as 
stated  above  (A.  3).  But  God  always  vouchsafed  the 
ministrations  of  the  angels  not  to  the  Jews  alone,  but  to  all 
nations:  for  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  xvii.  14) :  Over  every  nation 
He  set  a  ruler.  Also  on  all  nations  He  bestows  temporal 
goods,  which  are  of  less  account  with  God  than  spiritual 
goods.  Therefore  He  should  have  given  the  Law  also  to 
all  peoples. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  (Rom.  iii.  1,2):  What  advan- 
tage then  hath  the  Jew  ?  .  .  .  Much  every  way.  First 
indeed,  because  the  words  of  God  were  committed  to  them  :  and 
(Ps.  cxlvii.  9) :  He  hath  not  done  in  like  manner  to  every 
nation  :  and  His  judgments  He  hath  not  made  manifest  unto 
them. 

I  answer  that,  It  might  be  assigned  as  a  reason  for  the 
Law  being  given  to  the  Jews  rather  than  to  other  peoples, 
that  the  Jewish  people  alone  remained  faithful  to  the 
worship  of  one  God,  while  the  others  turned  away  to  idolatry ; 
wherefore  the  latter  were  unworthy  to  receive  the  Law, 
lest  a  holy  thing  should  be  given  to  dogs. 

But  this  reason  does  not  seem  fitting:  because  that 
people  turned  to  idolatry,  even  after  the  Law  had  been  made, 
which  was  more  grievous,  as  is  clear  from  Exod.  xxxii.  and 
from  Amos  v.  25,  26:  Did  you  offer  victims  and  sacrifices  to 
Me  in  the  desert  for  forty  years,  0  house  of  Israel  ?  But  you 
carried  a  tabernacle  for  your  Moloch,  and  the  image  of  your 
idols,  the  star  of  your  god,  which  you  made  to  yourselves. 
Moreover  it  is  stated  expressly  (Deut.  ix.  6) :  Know  therefore 
that  the  Lord  thy  God  giveth  thee  not  this  excellent  land  in  pos- 
session for  thy  justices,  for  thou  art  a  very  stiff-necked  people  : 
but  the  real  reason  is  given  in  the  preceding  verse:  That  the 
Lord  might  accomplish  His  word,  which  He  promised  by  oath 
to  thy  fathers  Abraham,  Isaac,  and  Jacob. 


93  THE  OLD  LAW  Q.  98.  Art.  4 

What  this  promise  was  is  shown  by  the  Apostle,  who  says 
(Gal.  iii.  16)  that  to  Abraham  were  the  promises  rnade  and  to 
his  seed.  He  saith  not,  '  And  to  his  seeds'  as  of  many  :  hut 
as  of  one,  '  And  to  thy  seed,  which  is  Christ.'  And  so  God 
vouchsafed  both  the  Law  and  other  special  boons  to  that 
people,  on  account  of  the  promise  made  to  their  fathers 
that  Christ  should  be  born  of  them.  For  it  was  fitting  that 
the  people,  of  whom  Christ  was  to  be  born,  should  be  sig- 
nahzed  by  a  special  sanctification,  according  to  the  words 
of  Levit.  xix.  2:  Be  ye  holy,  because  I  .  .  .  am  holy. — Nor 
again  was  it  on  account  of  the  merit  of  Abraham  himself 
that  this  promise  was  made  to  him,  viz.,  that  Christ 
should  be  born  of  his  seed:  but  of  gratuitous  election  and 
vocation.  Hence  it  is  written  (Isa.  xli.  2) :  Who  hath  raised 
up  the  just  one  from  the  east,  hath  called  him  to  follow  him  ? 

It  is  therefore  evident  that  it  was  merely  from  gratuitous 
election  that  the  patriarchs  received  the  promise,  and  that 
the  people  sprung  from  them  received  the  law;  according  to 
Deut.  iv.  36,37:  Ye  did  (Vulg., — Thou  didst)  hear  His  words 
out  of  the  midst  of  the  fire,  because  He  loved  thy  fathers,  and 
chose  their  seed  after  them. — And  if  again  it  be  asked  why  He 
chose  this  people,  and  not  another,  that  Christ  might  be 
born  thereof;  a  fitting  answer  is  given  by  Augustine  in  his 
commentary  on  John  vi.  44  [Tract,  xxvi.) :  Why  He  draiveth 
one  and  draweth  not  another,  seek  not  thou  to  judge,  if  thou  wish 
not  to  err. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Although  the  salvation,  which  was  to  come 
through  Christ,  was  prepared  for  all  nations,  yet  it  was 
necessary  that  Christ  should  be  born  of  one  people,  which, 
for  this  reason,  was  privileged  above  other  peoples;  ac- 
cording to  Rom.  ix.  4:  To  whom,  namely  the  Jews,  belongeth 
the  adoption  as  of  children  [of  God),  .  .  .  and  the  testament,  and 
the  giving  of  the  Law  ;  .  .  .  whose  are  the  fathers,  and  of  whom 
is  Christ  according  to  the  flesh. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Respect  of  persons  takes  place  in  those 
things  which  are  given  according  to  due ;  but  it  has  no  place 
in  those  things  which  are  bestowed  gratuitously.  Because 
he  who,  out  of  generosity,  gives  of  his  own  to  one  and  not 


Q.  98.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  94 

to  another,  is  not  a  respecter  of  persons :  but  if  he  were  a 
dispenser  of  goods  held  in  common,  and  were  not  to  dis- 
tribute them  according  to  personal  merits,  he  would  be  a 
respecter  of  persons.  Now  God  bestows  the  benefits  of 
salvation  on  the  human  race  gratuitously:  wherefore  He 
is  not  a  respecter  of  persons,  if  He  gives  them  to  some 
rather  than  to  others.  Hence  Augustine  says  [De  Prcedest. 
Sanct.  viii.) :  All  whom  God  teaches,  He  teaches  out  of  pity  ; 
hut  whom  He  teaches  not,  out  of  justice  He  teaches  not :  for 
this  is  due  to  the  condemnation  of  the  human  race  for  the 
sin  of  the  first  parent. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  benefits  of  grace  are  forfeited  by  man 
on  account  of  sin:  but  not  the  benefits  of  nature.  Among 
the  latter  are  the  ministries  of  the  angels,  which  the  very 
order  of  various  natures  demands,  viz.,  that  the  lowest  beings 
be  governed  through  the  intermediate  beings :  and  also  bodily 
aids,  which  God  vouchsafes  not  only  to  men,  but  also  to 
beasts,  according  to  Ps.  xxxv.  7 :  Men  and  beasts  Thou  wilt 
preserve,  0  Lord. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  all  men  were  bound  to  observe  the  old 

LAW  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  all  men  were  bound  to  observe 
the  Old  Law.  Because  whoever  is  subject  to  the  king, 
must  needs  be  subject  to  his  law.  But  the  Old  Law  was 
given  by  God,  Who  is  King  of  all  the  earth  (Ps.  xlvi.  8) . 
Therefore  all  the  inhabitants  of  the  earth  were  bound  to 
observe  the  Law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Jews  could  not  be  saved  without 
observing  the  Old  Law :  for  it  is  written  (Deut.  xxvii.  26) : 
Cursed  be  he  that  abideth  not  in  the  words  of  this  law,  and 
fulfilleth  them  not  in  work,  li  therefore  other  men  could  be 
saved  without  the  observance  of  the  Old  Law,  the  Jews 
would  be  in  a  worse  plight  than  other  men. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Gentiles  were  admitted  to  the  Jewish 
ritual  and  to  the  observances  of  the  Law:  for  it  is  written 


95  THE  OLD  LAW  Q.  98.  Art.  5 

(Exod.  xii.  48) :  //  any  stranger  be  willing  to  dwell  among  you, 
and  to  keep  the  Phase  of  the  Lord,  all  his  males  shall  first  he 
circumcised,  and  then  shall  he  celebrate  it  according  to  the 
mamier  ;  and  he  shall  be  as  he  that  is  born  in  the  land.  But 
it  would  have  been  useless  to  admit  strangers  to  the  legal 
observances  according  to  the  Divine  ordinance,  if  they 
could  have  been  saved  without  the  observance  of  the  Law. 
Therefore  none  could  be  saved  without  observing  the  Law. 
On  the  contrary,  Dionysius  says  (Coel.  Hier.  ix )  that  many 
of  the  Gentiles  were  brought  back  to  God  by  the  angels. 
But  it  is  clear  that  the  Gentiles  did  not  observe  the  Law. 
Therefore  some  could  be  saved  without  observing  the  Law. 

/  answer  that.  The  Old  Law  showed  forth  the  precepts 
of  the  natural  law,  and  added  certain  precepts  of  its  own. 
Accordingly,  as  to  those  precepts  of  the  natural  law  con- 
tained in  the  Old  Law,  all  were  bound  to  observe  the  Old 
Law;  not  because  they  belonged  to  the  Old  Law,  but  because 
they  belonged  to  the  natural  law.  But  as  to  those  precepts 
which  were  added  by  the  Old  Law,  they  were  not  binding 
on  any  save  the  Jewish  people  alone. 

The  reason  of  this  is  because  the  Old  Law,  as  stated  above 
(A.  4),  was  given  to  the  Jewish  people,  that  it  might  receive 
a  prerogative  of  holiness,  in  reverence  for  Christ  Who  was 
to  be  born  of  that  people.  Now  whatever  laws  are  enacted 
for  the  special  sanctification  of  certain  ones,  are  binding  on 
them  alone:  thus  clerics  who  are  set  aside  for  the  service 
of  God  are  bound  to  certain  obligations  to  which  the  laity 
are  not  bound;  likewise  religious  are  bound  by  their  profes- 
sion to  certain  works  of  perfection,  to  which  people  living 
in  the  world  are  not  bound.  In  like  manner  this  people 
was  bound  to  certain  special  observances,  to  which  other 
peoples  were  not  bound.  Wherefore  it  is  written  (Deut. 
xviii.  13) :  Thou  shall  be  perfect  and  without  spot  before  the 
Lord  thy  God  :  and  for  this  reason  they  used  a  kind  of  form 
of  profession,  as  appears  from  Deut.  xxvi.  3:  /  profess  this 
day  before  the  Lord  thy  God,  etc. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Whoever  are  subject  to  a  king,  are  bound 
to  observe  his  law  which  he  makes  for  all  in  general.      But 


Q.  98.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  96 

if  he  orders  certain  things  to  be  observed  by  the  servants 
of  his  household,  others  are  not  bound  thereto. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  more  a  man  is  united  to  God,  the  better 
his  state  becomes:  wherefore  the  more  the  Jewish  people 
were  bound  to  the  worship  of  God,  the  greater  their  excel- 
lence over  other  peoples.  Hence  it  is  written  (Deut.  iv.  8) : 
What  other  nation  is  there  so  renowned  that  hath  ceremonies 
and  just  judgments,  and  all  the  law  ?  In  like  manner,  from 
this  point  of  view,  the  state  of  clerics  is  better  than  that  of 
the  laity,  and  the  state  of  religious  than  that  of  folk  living 
in  the  world. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  Gentiles  obtained  salvation  more  per- 
fectly and  more  securely  under  the  observances  of  the  Law 
than  under  the  mere  natural  law  :  and  for  this  reason 
they  were  admitted  to  them.  So  too  the  laity  are  now  ad- 
mitted to  the  ranks  of  the  clergy,  and  secular  persons  to 
those  of  the  religious^  although  they  can  be  saved  without 
this. 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  the  old  law  was  suitably  given  at  the  time 

OF   MOSES  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  was  not  suitably 
given  at  the  time  of  Moses.  Because  the  Old  Law  disposed 
man  for  the  salvation  which  was  to  come  through  Christ,  as 
stated  above  (AA.  2,  3).  But  man  needed  this  salutary 
remedy  immediately  after  he  had  sinned.  Therefore  the 
Law  should  have  been  given  immediately  after  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Old  Law  was  given  for  the  sanctifi- 
cation  of  those  from  whom  Christ  was  to  be  born.  Now 
the  promise  concerning  the  seed,  which  is  Christ  (Gal.  iii.  16) 
was  first  made  to  Abraham,  as  related  in  Gen.  xii.  7.  There- 
fore the  Law  should  have  been  given  at  once  at  the  time  of 
Abraham. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  as  Christ  was  born  of  those  alone  who 
descended  from  Noe  through  Abraham,  to  whom  the 
promise  was  made;   so  was   He  born  of  no  other  of  the 


97  THE  OLD  LAW  Q.  98.  Art.  6 

descendants  of  Abraham  but  David,  to  whom  the  promise 
was  renewed,  according  to  2  Kings  xxiii.  i :  The  man  to 
whom  it  was  appointed  concerning  the  Christ  of  the  God  of 
Jacob  .  .  .  said.  Therefore  the  Old  Law  should  have  been 
given  after  David,  just  as  it  was  given  after  Abraham. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Gal.  iii.  ig)  that  the 
Law  was  set  because  of  transgressions,  until  the  seed  should 
come,  to  whom  He  made  the  promise,  being  ordained  by  angels 
in  the  hand  of  a  Mediator  : — ordained,  i.e.,  given  in  orderly 
fashion,  as  the  gloss  explains.  Therefore  it  was  fitting  that 
the  Old  Law  should  be  given  in  this  order  of  time. 

/  answer  that.  It  was  most  fitting  for  the  Law  to  be  given 
at  the  time  of  Moses.  The  reason  for  this  may  be  taken 
from  two  things  in  respect  of  which  every  law  is  imposed 
on  two  kinds  of  men.  Because  it  is  imposed  on  some  men 
who  are  hard-hearted  and  proud,  whom  the  law  restrains 
and  tames:  and  it  is  imposed  on  good  men,  who,  through 
being  instructed  by  the  law,  are  helped  to  fulfil  what  they 
desire  to  do.  Hence  it  was  fitting  that  the  Law  should 
be  given  at  such  a  time  as  would  be  appropriate  for  the 
overcoming  of  man's  pride.  For  man  was  proud  of  two 
things,  viz.,  of  knowledge  and  of  power.  He  was  proud 
of  his  knowledge,  as  though  his  natural  reason  could  suffice 
him  for  salvation:  and  accordingly,  in  order  that  his  pride 
might  be  overcome  in  this  matter,  man  was  left  to  the 
guidance  of  his  reason  without  the  help  of  a  written  law: 
and  man  was  able  to  learn  from  experience  that  his  reason 
was  deficient,  since  about  the  time  of  Abraham  man  had 
fallen  headlong  into  idolatry  and  the  most  shameful  vices. 
Wherefore,  after  those  times,  it  was  necessary  for  a  written 
law  to  be  given  as  a  remedy  for  human  ignorance :  because 
by  the  Law  is  the  knowledge  of  sin  (Rom.  iii.  20). — But,  after 
man  had  been  instructed  by  the  Law,  his  pride  was  con- 
vinced of  his  weakness,  through  his  being  unable  to  fulfil 
what  he  knew.  Hence,  as  the  Apostle  concludes  (Rom.  viii. 
3,  4),  what  the  Law  could  not  do  in  that  it  was  weak  through 
the  flesh,  God  sent  (Vulg., — sending)  His  own  Son,  .  .  .  that  the 
justification  of  the  Law  might  be  fulfilled  in  us. 

II.  3  '7 


Q.  98.  Art.  6     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  98 

With  regard  to  good  men,  the  Law  was  given  to  them  as 
a  help;  which  was  most  needed  by  the  people,  at  the  time 
when  the  natural  law  began  to  be  obscured  on  account  of 
the  exuberance  of  sin:  for  it  was  fitting  that  this  help 
should  be  bestowed  on  men  in  an  orderly  manner,  so  that 
they  might  be  led  from  imperfection  to  perfection;  where- 
fore it  was  becoming  that  the  Old  Law  should  be  given 
between  the  law  of  nature  and  the  law  of  grace. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  It  was  not  fitting  for  the  Old  Law  to  be 
given  at  once  after  the  sin  of  the  first  man:  both  because 
man  was  so  confident  in  his  own  reason,  that  he  did  not 
acknowledge  his  need  of  the  Old  Law;  and  because  as  yet 
the  dictate  of  the  natural  law  was  not  darkened  by  habitual 
sinning. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  law  should  not  be  given  save  to  the  people, 
since  it  is  a  general  precept,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  AA. 
2,  3) ;  wherefore  at  the  time  of  Abraham  God  gave  men 
certain  familiar,  and,  as  it  were,  household  precepts:  but 
when  Abraham's  descendants  had  multiplied,  so  as  to  form 
a  people,  and  when  they  had  been  freed  from  slavery,  it 
was  fitting  that  they  should  be  given  a  law;  for  slaves  are 
not  that  part  of  the  people  or  state  to  which  it  is  fitting  for  the 
law  to  he  directed,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (Polit.  iii.). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Since  the  Law  had  to  be  given  to  the 
people,  not  only  those,  of  whom  Christ  was  born,  received 
the  Law,  but  the  whole  people,  who  were  marked  with  the 
seal  of  circumcision,  which  was  the  sign  of  the  promise 
made  to  Abraham,  and  in  which  he  believed,  according  to 
Rom.  iv.  II:  hence  even  before  David,  the  Law  had  to 
be  given  to  that  people  as  soon  as  they  were  collected 
together. 


QUESTION  XCIX. 

OF  THE  PRECEPTS  OF  THE  OLD  LAW. 

{In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  precepts  of  the  Old  Law;  and 
(i)  how  they  are  distinguished  from  one  another;  (2)  each 
kind  of  precept.  Under  the  first  head  there  are  six  points 
of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether  the  Old  Law  contained  several 
precepts  or  only  one  ?  (2)  Whether  the  Old  Law  con- 
tains any  moral  precepts  ?  (3)  Whether  it  contains  cere- 
monial    precepts    in    addition    to    the    moral     precepts  ? 

(4)  Whether  besides  these   it  contains  judicial   precepts  ? 

(5)  Whether  it  contains  any  others  besides  these  ?  (6)  How 
the  Old  Law  induced  men  to  keep  its  precepts. 

First  Article, 
whether  the  old  law  contains  only  one  precept  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  contains  but  one 
precept.  Because  a  law  is  nothing  else  than  a  precept,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  XC,  AA.  2,  3).  Now  there  is  but  one  Old 
Law.     Therefore  it  contains  but  one  precept. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  xiii.  9) :  //  there 
be  any  other  commandment,  it  is  comprised  in  this  word  : 
Thou  shalt  love  thy  neighbour  as  thyself.  But  this  is  only 
one  commandment.  Therefore  the  Old  Law  contained 
but  one  commandment. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  it  is  written  (Matth.  vii.  12)  :  All  things 
.  .  .  whatsoever  you  would  that  men  should  do  to  you,  do  you 
also  to  them.     For  this  is  the  Law  and  the  prophets.     But 

99 


Q.  99.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  100 

the  whole  of  the  Old  Law  is  comprised  in  the  Law  and  the 
prophets.  Therefore  the  whole  of  the  Old  Law  contains 
but  one  commandment. 

On  the  contrary y  The  Apostle  says  (Ephes.  ii.  15) :  Making 
void  the  Law  of  commandments  contained  in  decrees  :  where 
he  is  referring  to  the  Old  Law,  as  the  gloss  comments  on  the 
passage.  Therefore  the  Old  Law  comprises  many  com- 
mandments. 

/  answer  that,  Since  a  precept  of  law  is  binding,  it  is  about 
something  which  must  be  done:  and,  that  a  thing  must  be 
done,  arises  from  the  necessity  of  some  end.  Hence  it  is 
evident  that  a  precept  implies,  in  its  very  idea,  relation  to 
an  end,  in  so  far  as  a  thing  is  commanded  as  being  necessary 
or  expedient  to  an  end.  Now  many  things  may  happen  to 
be  necessary  or  expedient  to  an  end;  and,  accordingly, 
precepts  may  be  given  about  various  things  as  being 
ordained  to  one  end.  Consequently  we  must  say  that 
all  the  precepts  of  the  Old  Law  are  one  in  respect  of  their 
relation  to  one  end:  and  yet  they  are  many  in  respect 
of  the  diversity  of  those  things  that  are  ordained  to 
that  end. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  Old  Law  is  said  to  be  one  as  being 
ordained  to  one  end:  yet  it  comprises  various  precepts, 
according  to  the  diversity  of  the  things  which  it  directs  to 
the  end.  Thus  also  the  art  of  building  is  one  according 
to  the  unity  of  its  end,  because  it  aims  at  the  building  of 
a  house:  and  yet  it  contains  various  rules,  according  to  the 
variety  of  acts  ordained  thereto. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  the  Apostle  says  (i  Tim.  i.  5),  the  end  of 
the  commandment  is  charity  ;  since  every  law  aims  at  estab- 
lishing friendship,  either  between  man  and  man,  or  between 
man  and  God.  Wherefore  the  whole  Law  is  comprised 
in  this  one  commandment.  Thou  shall  love  thy  neighbour  as 
thyself,  as  expressing  the  end  of  all  commandments:  because 
love  of  one's  neighbour  includes  love  of  God,  when  we 
love  our  neighbour  for  God's  sake.  Hence  the  ApostJe 
put  this  commandment  in  place  of  the  two  which  are  about 
the  love  of  God  and  of  one's  neighbour,  and  of  which  Our 


loi  PRECEPTS  OF  THE  OLD  LAW      Q  99-  Art.  2 

Lord  said  (Matth.  xxii.   40) :   On  these  two  commandments 
dependeth  the  whole  Law  and  the  prophets. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  in  Ethio.  ix.,  friendship  towards 
another  arises  from  friendship  towards  oneself,  in  so  far  as  man 
looks  on  another  as  on  himself.  Hence  when  it  is  said, 
All  things  whatsoever  you  would  that  men  should  do  to  you, 
do  you  also  to  them,  this  is  an  explanation  of  the  rule  of  neigh- 
bourly love  contained  implicitly  in  the  words,  Thou  shall 
love  thy  neighbour  as  thyself :  so  that  it  is  an  explanation 
of  this  commandment. 

Second  Article, 
whether  the  old  law  contains  moral  precepts  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  contains  no  moral 
precepts.  For  the  Old  Law  is  distinct  from  the  law  of 
nature,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCL,  AA.  4,  5;  Q.  XCVIIL, 
A.  5).  But  the  moral  precepts  belong  to  the  law  of  nature. 
Therefore  they  do  not  belong  to  the  Old  Law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Divine  law  should  have  come  to  man's 
assistance  where  human  reason  fails  him:  as  is  evident  in 
regard  to  things  that  are  of  faith,  which  are  above  reason. 
But  man's  reason  seems  to  suffice  for  the  moral  precepts. 
Therefore  the  moral  precepts  do  not  belong  to  the  Old  Law, 
which  is  a  Divine  law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Old  Law  is  said  to  be  the  letter  that 
killeth  (2  Cor.  iii.  6).  But  the  moral  precepts  do  not  kill, 
but  quicken,  according  to  Ps.  cxviii.  93:  Thy  justifications 
I  will  never  forget,  for  by  them  Thou  hast  given  me  life. 
Therefore  the  moral  precepts  do  not  belong  to  the  Old  Law. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  wiitten  (Ecclus.  xvii.  9) :  Moreover, 
He  gave  them  discipline  (Douay, — instructions)  and  the  law 
of  life  for  an  inheritance.  Now  discipline  belongs  to  morals; 
for  the  gloss  on  Heb.  xii.  11:  Now  all  chastisement  [disci- 
plina),  etc.,  says:  Discipline  is  an  exercise  in  morals  by  means 
of  difficulties.  Therefore  the  Law  which  was  given  by  God 
comprised  moral  precepts. 


Q.  99.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  102 

/  answer  that,  The  Old  Law  contained  some  moral  pre- 
cepts; as  is  evident  from  Exod.  xx.  13,  15:  Thou  shalt  not 
kill,  Thou  shalt  not  steal.  This  was  reasonable:  because, 
just  as  the  principal  intention  of  human  law  is  to  create 
friendship  between  man  and  man;  so  the  chief  intention 
01  the  Divine  law  is  to  establish  man  in  friendship  with  God. 
Now  since  likeness  is  the  reason  of  love,  according  to 
Ecclus.  xiii.  19:  Every  beast  loveth  its  like;  there  cannot 
possibly  be  any  friendship  of  man  to  God,  Who  is  supremely 
good,  unless  man  become  good:  wherefore  it  is  written 
(Levit.  xix.  2;  cf.  xi.  45):  You  shall  be  holy,  for  I  am  holy. 
But  the  goodness  of  man  is  virtue,  which  makes  its  subject 
good  (Ethic,  ii.).  Therefore  it  was  necessary  for  the  Old 
Law  to  include  precepts  about  acts  of  virtue :  and  these  are 
the  mora]  precepts  of  the  Law. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  Old  Law  is  distinct  from  the  natural 
law,  not  as  being  altogether  different  from  it,  but  as 
something  added  thereto.  For  just  as  grace  presupposes 
nature,  so  must  the  Divine  law  presuppose  the  natural 
law. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  was  fitting  that  the  Divine  law  should 
come  to  man's  assistance  not  only  in  those  things  for  which 
reason  is  insufficient,  but  also  in  those  things  in  which  human 
reason  may  happen  to  be  impeded.  Now  human  reason 
could  not  go  astray  in  the  abstract,  as  to  the  universal 
piinciples  of  the  natural  law;  but  through  bsing  habituated 
to  sin,  it  became  obscured  in  the  point  of  things  to  be  done 
in  detail.  But  with  regard  to  the  other  moral  precepts, 
which  are  like  conclusions  drawn  from  the  universal  prin- 
ciples of  the  natural  law,  the  reason  of  many  men  went 
astray,  to  the  extent  of  judging  to  be  lawful,  things  that  are 
evil  in  themselves.  Hence  there  was  need  for  the  authority 
of  the  Divine  law  to  rescue  man  from  both  these  defects. 
Thus  among  the  articles  of  faith  not  only  are  those  things 
set  forth  to  which  reason  cannot,  reach,  such  as  the  Trinity 
of  the  Godhead;  but  also  those  to  which  right  reason  can 
attain,  such  as  the  Unity  of  the  Godhead;  in  order  to  re- 
move the  manifold  errors  to  which  reason  is  liable. 


103  PRECEPTS  OF  THE  OLD  LAW    Q.  99.  Art.  ^ 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  Augustine  proves  (De  Spiritu  ct  Litera), 
even  the  letter  of  the  law  is  said  to  be  the  occasion  of  death, 
as  to  the  moral  precepts;  in  so  far  as,  to  wit,  it  prescribes 
what  is  good,  without  furnishing  the  aid  of  grace  for  its 
fulfilment. 

Third  Article. 

whether  the  old  law  comprises  ceremonial,  besides 

moral,  precepts  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  does  not  comprise 
ceremonial,  besides  moral,  precepts.  For  every  law  that 
is  given  to  man  is  for  the  purpose  of  directing  human  actions. 
Now  human  actions  are  called  moral,  as  stated  above  (Q.  L, 
A.  3).  Therefore  it  seems  that  the  Old  Law  given  to  men 
should  not  comprise  other  than  moral  precepts. 

Obj,  2.  Further,  those  precepts  that  are  styled  ceremonial 
seem  to  refer  to  the  Divine  worship.  But  Divine  worship 
is  the  act  of  a  virtue,  viz.,  religion,  which,  as  Tully  says 
[Rhet.  ii.)  offers  worship  and  ceremony  to  the  Godhead.  Since, 
then,  the  moral  precepts  are  about  acts  of  virtue,  as  stated 
above  (A.  2),  it  seems  that  the  ceremonial  precepts  should 
not  be  distinct  from  the  moral. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  ceremonial  precepts  seem  to  be  those 
which  signify  something  figuratively.  But,  as  Augustine 
observes  [De  Doctr.  Christ,  ii.),  of  all  signs  employed  by  men 
words  hold  the  first  place.  Therefore  there  was  no  need  for 
the  Law  to  contain  ceremonial  precepts  about  certain 
figurative  actions. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Deut.  iv.  13,  14) :  Ten  words 
.  .  .  He  wrote  in  two  tables  of  stone  ;  and  He  commanded  me 
at  that  time  that  I  should  teach  you  the  ceremonies  and  judg- 
ments which  you  shall  do.  But  the  ten  commandments  of 
the  Law  are  moral  precepts.  Therefore  besides  the  moral 
precepts  there  are  others  which  are  ceremonial. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  2),  the  Divine  law  is 
instituted  chiefly  in  order  to  direct  men  to  God;  while 
human  law  is  instituted  chiefly  in   order  to  direct  men  in 


Q.  99-  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  '^  104 

relation  to  one  another.  Hence  human  laws  have  not  con- 
cerned themselves  with  the  institution  of  anything  relating 
to  Divine  worship  except  as  affecting  the  common  good  of 
mankind:  and  for  this  reason  they  have  devised  many  in- 
stitutions relating  to  Divine  matters,  according  as  it  seemed 
expedient  for  the  formation  of  human  morals ;  as  may  be  seen 
in  the  rites  of  the  Gentiles.  On  the  other  hand  the  Divine 
law  directed  men  to  one  another  according  to  the  demands 
of  that  order  whereby  man  is  directed  to  God,  which  order 
was  the  chief  aim  of  that  law.  Now  man  is  directed  to  God 
not  only  by  the  interior  acts  of  the  mind,  which  are  faith, 
hope,  and  love,  but  also  by  certain  external  works,  whereby 
man  makes  profession  of  his  subjection  to  God:  and  it  is 
these  works  that  are  said  to  belong  to  the  Divine  worship. 
This  worship  is  called  ceremony, — the  munia,  i.e.,  gifts,  of 
Ceres  (who  was  the  goddess  of  fruits),  as  some  say:  because, 
at  first,  offerings  were  made  to  God  from  the  fruits: — or 
because,  as  Maximus  Valerius  states,  the  word  ceremony 
was  introduced  among  the  Latins,  to  signify  the  Divine 
worship,  being  derived  from  a  town  near  Rome  called 
Caere :  since,  when  Rome  was  taken  by  the  Gauls,  the  sacred 
chattels  of  the  Romans  were  taken  thither  and  most  care- 
fully preserved.  Accordingly  those  precepts  of  the  Law 
which  refer  to  the  Divine  worship  are  specially  called 
ceremonial. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Human  acts  extend  also  to  the  Divine 
worship:  and  therefore  the  Old  Law  given  to  man  contains 
precepts  about  these  matters  also. 

Reply  Ohj,  2.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XCL,  A.  3),  the  pre- 
cepts of  the  natural  law  are  general,  and  require  to  be  de- 
termined :  and  they  are  determined  both  by  human  law  and 
by  Divine  law.  And  just  as  these  very  determinations  which 
are  made  by  human  law  are  said  to  be,  not  of  natural,  but 
of  positive  law;  so  the  determinations  of  the  precepts  of 
the  natural  law,  effected  by  the  Divine  law,  are  distinct 
from  the  moral  precepts  which  belong  to  the  natural  law. 
Wherefore  to  worship  God,  since  it  is  an  act  of  virtue,  be- 
longs to  a  moral  precept;  but  the  determination  of  this 


105  PRECEPTS  OF  THE  OLD  LAW     Q.  99.  Art.  4 

precept,  namely  that  He  is  to  be  worshipped  by  such  and 
such  sacrifices,  and  such  and  such  offerings,  belongs  to  the 
ceremonial  precepts.  Consequently  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts are  distinct  from  the  moral  precepts. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  Dionysius  says  (C03L  Hier.  i.),  the  things 
of  God  cannot  be  manifested  to  men  except  by  means  of 
sensible  similitudes.  Now  these  similitudes  move  the  soul 
more  when  they  are  not  only  expressed  in  words,  but  also 
offered  to  the  senses.  Wherefore  the  things  of  God  are  set 
forth  in  the  Scriptures  not  only  by  similitudes  expressed  in 
words,  as  in  the  case  of  metaphorical  expressions;  but  also 
by  similitudes  of  things  set  before  the  eyes,  which  pertains 
to  the  ceremonial  precepts. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether,  besides  the  moral  and  ceremonial  precepts, 
there  are  also  judicial  precepts  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  are  no  judicial  precepts 
in  addition  to  the  moral  and  ceremonial  precepts  in  the  Old 
Law.  For  Augustine  says  (Contra  Faust,  vi.)  that  in  the 
Old  Law  there  are  precepts  concerning  the  life  we  have  to 
lead,  and  precepts  regarding  the  life  that  is  foreshadowed. 
Now  the  precepts  of  the  life  we  have  to  lead  are  moral 
precepts;  and  the  precepts  of  the  life  that  is  foreshadowed 
are  ceremonial.  Therefore  besides  these  two  kinds  of 
precepts  we  should  not  put  any  judicial  precepts  in  the 
Law. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  a  gloss  on  Ps.  cxviii.  102,  /  have  not  de- 
clined from  Thy  judgments,  says, — i.e.,  from  the  rule  of  life 
Thou  hast  set  for  me.  But  a  rule  of  life  belongs  to  the  moral 
precepts.  Therefore  the  judicial  precepts  should  not  be 
considered  as  distinct  from  the  moral  precepts. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  judgment  seems  to  be  an  act  of  justice, 
according  to  Ps.  xciii.  15 :  Until  justice  he  turned  into  judg- 
ment. But  acts  of  justice,  like  the  acts  of  other  virtues, 
belong  to  the  moral  precepts.     Therefore  the  moral  precepts 


Q.  99.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  106 

include  the  judicial  precepts,  and  consequently  should  not 
be  held  as  distinct  from  them. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Deut.  vi.  i) :  These  are  the 
precepts,  and  ceremonies,  and  judgments  :  where  precepts 
stands  for  moral  precepts  antonomastically.  Therefore  there 
are  judicial  precepts  besides  moral  and  ceremonial  precepts. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A A.  2,  3),  it  belongs  to 
the  Divine  law  to  direct  men  to  one  another  and  to  God. 
Now  each  of  these  belongs  in  the  abstract  to  the  dictates 
of  the  natural  law,  to  which  dictates  the  moral  precepts 
are  to  be  referred:  yet  each  of  them  has  to  be  determined 
by  Divine  or  human  law,  because  naturally  known  prin- 
ples  are  universal,  both  in  speculative  and  in  practical 
matters.  Accordingly  just  as  the  determination  of  the 
universal  principle  about  Divine  worship  is  effected  by  the 
ceremonial  precepts,  so  the  determination  of  the  general 
precepts  of  that  justice  which  is  to  be  observed  among  men 
is  effected  by  the  judicial  precepts. 

We  must  therefore  distinguish  three  kinds  of  precept  in 
the  Old  Law;  viz.,  moral  precepts,  which  are  dictated  by 
the  natural  law;  ceremonial  precepts,  which  are  determina- 
tions of  the  Divine  worship;  and  judicial  precepts,  which 
are  determinations  of  the  justice  to  be  maintained  among 
men.  Wherefore  the  Apostle  (Rom.  vii.  12)  after  saying 
that  the  Law  is  holy,  adds  that  the  commandment  is  just,  and 
holy,  and  good  :  just,  in  respect  of  the  judicial  precepts;  holy, 
with  regard  to  the  ceremonial  precepts  (since  the  word  sanctus 
— holy — is  applied  to  that  which  is  consecrated  to  God) ;  and 
good,  i.e.,  conducive  to  virtue,  as  to  the  moral  precepts. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Both  the  moral  and  the  judicial  precepts 
aim  at  the  ordering  of  human  life:  and  consequently  they 
are  both  comprised  under  one  of  the  heads  mentioned  by 
Augustine,  viz.,  under  the  precepts  of  the  life  we  have  to 
lead. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Judgment  denotes  execution  of  justice,  by 
an  application  of  the  reason  to  individual  cases  in  a  de- 
terminate way.  Hence  the  judicial  precepts  have  some- 
thing in  common  with  the  moral  precepts,  in  that  they  are 


107  PRECEPTS  OF  THE  OLD  LAW     Q.  99-  Art.  5 

derived  from  reason;  and  something  in  common  with  the 
ceremonial  precepts,  in  that  they  arc  determinations  of 
general  precepts.  This  explains  why  sometimes  judgments 
comprises  both  judicial  and  moral  precepts,  as  in  Deut.  v.  i : 
Hear  J  0  Israel,  the  ceremonies  and  judgments  ;  and  sometimes 
judicial  and  ceremonial  precepts,  as  in  Levit.  xviii.  4:  You 
shall  do  My  judgments,  and  shall  observe  My  precepts,  where 
precepts  denotes  moral  precepts,  while  judgments  refers  to 
judicial  and  ceremonial  precepts. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  act  of  justice,  in  general,  belongs  to 
the  moral  precepts;  but  its  determination  to  some  special 
kind  of  act  belongs  to  the  judicial  precepts. 


Fifth  Article. 

whether  the  old  law  contains  any  others  besides 
the  moral,  judicial,  and  ceremonial  precepts  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  contains  others 
besides  the  moral,  judicial,  and  ceremonial  precepts.  Be- 
cause the  judicial  precepts  belong  to  the  act  of  justice, 
which  is  between  man  and  man;  while  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts belong  to  the  act  of  religion,  whereby  God  is  worshipped. 
Now  besides  these  there  are  many  other  virtues,  viz.,  tem- 
perance, fortitude,  liberality,  and  several  others,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  LX.,  A.  5).  Therefore  besides  the  aforesaid  pre- 
cepts, the  Old  Law  should  comprise  others. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  it  is  written  (Deut.  xi.  i) :  Love  the  Lord 
thy  God,  and  observe  His  precepts  and  ceremonies,  His  judg- 
ments and  commandments.  Now  precepts  concern  moral 
matters,  as  stated  above  (A.  4).  Therefore  besides  the 
moral,  judicial,  and  ceremonial  precepts,  the  Law  contains 
others  which  are  called  commandments."^ 

Obj.  3.  Further,  it  is  written  (Deut.  vi.  17) :  Keep  the  pre- 
cepts of  the  Lord  thy  God,  and  the  testimonies  and  ceremonies 

*  The  commandments  {mandata)  spoken  of  here  and  in  the  body  of 
this  article  are  not  to  be  confused  with  the  Commandments  {j)rcrccptci)  in 
the  ordinary  acceptance  of  the  word. 


Q.  99-  Art.  5    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  108 

which  I  have  (Vulg., — He  hath)  commanded  thee.  Therefore 
in  addition  to  the  above,  the  Law  comprises  testimonies. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  it  is  written  (Ps.  cxviii.  93) :  Thy  justifi- 
cations (i.e..  Thy  Law,  according  to  a  gloss)  /  will  never  forget. 
Therefore  in  the  Old  Law  there  are  not  only  moral,  ceremonial, 
and  judicial  precepts,  but  also  others,  called  justifications. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Deut.  vi.  i) :  These  are  the 
precepts  and  ceremonies  and  judgments  which  the  Lord  your 
God  commanded  .  .  .  you.  And  these  words  are  placed  at 
the  beginning  of  the  Law.  Therefore  all  the  precepts  of 
the  Law  are  included  under  them. 

/  answer  that,  Some  things  are  included  in  the  Law  by  way 
of  precept ;  other  things,  as  being  ordained  to  the  fulfilment 
of  the  precepts.  Now  the  precepts  refer  to  things  which 
have  to  be  done :  and  to  their  fulfilment  man  is  induced  by 
two  considerations,  viz.,  the  authority  of  the  lawgiver,  and 
the  benefit  derived  from  the  fulfilment,  which  benefit  con- 
sists in  the  attainment  of  some  good,  useful,  pleasurable 
or  virtuous,  or  in  the  avoidance  of  some  contrary  evil. 
Hence  it  was  necessary  that  in  the  Old  Law  certain  things 
should  be  set  forth  to  indicate  the  authority  of  God  the  law- 
giver: e.g.,  Deut.  vi.  4:  Hear,  0  Israel,  the  Lord  our  God  is 
one  Lord  ;  and  Gen.  i.  i :  In  the  beginning  God  created  heaven 
and  earth :  and  these  are  called  testimonies. — Again  it  was 
necessary  that  in  the  Law  certain  rewards  should  be  ap- 
pointed for  those  who  observe  the  Law,  and  punishments 
for  those  who  transgress;  as  may  be  seen  in  Deut.  xxviii. : 
//  thou  wilt  hear  the  voice  of  the  Lord  Thy  God  .  .  .  He  will 
make  thee  higher  than  all  the  nations,  etc. :  and  these  are 
called  justifications,  according  as  God  punishes  or  rewards 
certain  ones  justly. 

The  things  that  have  to  be  done  do  not  come  under  the 
precept  except  in  so  far  as  they  have  the  character  of  a 
duty.  Now  a  duty  is  twofold:  one  according  to  the  rule 
of  reason;  the  other  according  to  the  rule  of  a  law  which 
prescribes  that  duty:  thus  the  Philosopher  distinguishes 
a  twofold  just, — moral  and  legal  [Ethic,  v.). 

Moral  duty  is  twofold:  because  reason  dictates  that  some- 


log  PRECEPTS  OF  THE  OLD  LAW     Q.  90  Art.  5 

thing  must  be  done,  either  as  being  so  necessary  that  with- 
out it  the  order  of  virtue  would  be  destroyed;  or  as  being 
useful  for  the  better  maintaining  of  the  order  of  virtue. 
And  in  this  sense  some  of  the  moral  precepts  are  expressed 
by  way  of  absolute  command  or  prohibition,  as  Thou  shall 
not  kill,  Thou  shalt  not  steal :  and  these  are  properly  called 
precepts.  Other  things  are  prescribed  or  forbidden,  not  as 
an  absolute  duty,  but  as  something  better  to  be  done. 
These  may  be  called  commandments  ;  because  they  are  ex- 
pressed by  way  of  inducement  and  persuasion:  an  example 
whereof  is  seen  in  Exod.  xxii.  26:  If  thou  take  of  thy  neighbour 
a  garment  in  pledge,  thou  shalt  give  it  him  again  before  sunset ; 
and  in  other  like  cases.  Wherefore  Jerome  [Prcefat.  in 
Comment,  super  Marc.)  says  that  justice  is  in  the  precepts, 
charity  in  the  commandments. — Duty  as  fixed  by  the  Law, 
belongs  to  the  judicial  precepts,  as  regards  human  affairs; 
to  the  ceremonial  precepts,  as  regards  Divine  matters. 

Nevertheless  those  ordinances  also  which  refer  to  punish- 
ments and  rewards  may  be  called  testimonies,  in  so  far  as 
they  testify  to  the  Divine  justice. — Again  all  the  precepts 
of  the  Law  may  be  styled  justifications,  as  being  executions 
of  legal  justice. — Furthermore  the  commandments  may  be 
distinguished  from  the  precepts,  so  that  those  things  be 
called  precepts  which  God  Himself  prescribed  ;  and  those 
things  commandments  which  He  enjoined  [mandavit]  through 
others,  as  the  very  word  seems  to  denote. 

From  this  it  is  clear  that  all  the  precepts  of  the  Law  are 
either  moral,  ceremonial,  or  judicial;  and  that  other  ordin- 
ances have  not  the  character  of  a  precept,  but  are  directed 
to  the  observance  of  the  precepts,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Justice  alone,  of  all  the  virtues,  implies  the 
notion  of  duty.  Consequently  moral  matters  are  determin- 
able by  law  in  so  far  as  they  belong  to  justice:  of  which 
virtue  religion  is  a  part,  as  Tully  says  {Rhet.  ii.).  Where- 
fore the  legal  just  cannot  be  anything  foreign  to  the  cere- 
monial and  judicial  precepts. 

The  Replies  to  the  other  Objections  are  clear  from  what 
has  been  said. 


Q.  99-  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  no 


Sixth  Article. 

whether  the  old  law  should  have  induced  men  to  the 
observance  of  its  precepts,  by  means  of  temporal 
promises  and  threats  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  should  not  have 
induced  men  to  the  observance  of  its  precepts,  by  means  of 
temporal  promises  and  threats.  For  the  purpose  of  the 
Divine  law  is  to  subject  man  to  God  by  fear  and  love :  hence 
it  is  written  (Deut.  x.  12) :  And  now,  Israel,  what  doth  the 
Lord  thy  God  require  of  thee,  hut  that  thou  fear  the  Lord  thy 
God,  and  walk  in  His  ways,  and  love  Him  ?  But  the  desire 
for  temporal  goods  leads  man  away  from  God :  for  Augustine 
says  {Qq.  83),  that  covetousness  is  the  bane  of  charity.  There- 
fore temporal  promises  and  threats  seem  to  be  contrary  to 
the  intention  of  a  lawgiver:  and  this  makes  a  law  worthy 
of  rejection,  as  the  Philosopher  declares  (Polit.  ii.). 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Divine  law  is  more  excellent  than 
human  law.  Now,  in  sciences,  we  notice  that  the  loftier 
the  science,  the  higher  the  means  of  persuasion  that  it 
employs.  Therefore,  since  human  law  employs  temporal 
threats  and  promises,  as  means  of  persuading  man,  the 
Divine  law  should  have  used,  not  these,  but  more  lofty  means. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  reward  of  righteousness  and  the 
punishment  of  guilt  cannot  be  that  which  befalls  equally 
the  good  and  the  wicked.  But  as  stated  in  Eccles.  ix.  2, 
all  temporal  things  equally  happen  to  the  just  and  to  the  wicked, 
to  the  good  and  to  the  evil,  to  the  clean  and  to  the  unclean,  to 
him  that  offereth  victims,  and  to  him  that  despiseth  sacrifices. 
Therefore  temporal  goods  or  evils  are  not  suitably  set  forth 
as  punishments  or  rewards  of  the  commandments  of  the 
Divine  law. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  (Isa.  i.  19,  20) :  If  you  he 
willing,  and  will  hearken  to  Me,  you  shall  eat  the  good  things 
of  the  land.  But  if  you  will  not,  and  will  provoke  Me  to 
wrath  ;  the  sword  shall  devour  you. 


Ill  PRECEPTS  OF  THE  OLD  LAW     Q.  99-  Art.  6 

/  answer  that,  As  in  speculative  sciences  men  are  per- 
suaded to  assent  to  the  conclusions  by  means  of  syllogistic 
arguments,  so  too  in  every  law,  men  are  persuaded  to  observe 
its  precepts  by  means  of  punishments  and  rewards.     Now 
it  is  to  be  observed  that,  in  speculative  sciences,  the  means 
of  persuasion  are  adapted  to  the  conditions  of  the  pupil: 
wherefore  the  process  of  argument  in  sciences  should  be 
ordered  becomingly,  so  that   the  instruction  is  based  on 
principles  more  generally  known.     And  thus  also  he  who 
would  persuade  a  man  to  the  observance  of  any  precepts, 
needs  to  move  him  at  first  by  things  for  which  he  has  an 
affection;  just  as  children  are  induced  to  do  something,  by 
means  of  little  childish  gifts.     Now  it  has  been  said  above 
(Q.  XCVIIL,  AA.  I,  2,  3)  that  the  Old  Law  disposed  men 
to  (the  coming  of)  Christ,  as  the  imperfect  disposes  to  the 
perfect,  wherefore  it  was  given  to  a  people  as  yet  imperfect 
in  comparison  to  the  perfection  which  was  to  result  from 
Christ's  coming:  and  for  this  reason,  that  people  is  compared 
to  a  child  that  is  still  under  a  pedagogue  (Gal.  iii.  24).     But 
the  perfection  of  man  consists  in  his  despising  temporal 
things  and  cleaving  to  things  spiritual,  as  is  clear  from  the 
words  of  the  Apostle  (Phil.  iii.  13,  15) :  Forgetting  the  things 
that  are  behind,  I  stretch  (Vulg., — and  stretching)  forth  myself 
to  those  that  are  before.  .  .  .     Let  us  therefore,  as  many  as  are 
perfect,    be   thus    minded.     Those    who    are    yet    imperfect 
desire   temporal   goods,    albeit   in   subordination   to    God: 
whereas  the  perverse  place  their  end  in  temporalities.     It 
was  therefore  fitting  that  the  Old  Law  should  conduct  men 
to  God  by  means  of  temporal  goods  for  which  the  imperfect 
have  an  affection. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Covetousness  whereby  man  places  his  end 
in  temporalities,  is  the  bane  of  charity.  But  the  attainment 
of  temporal  goods  which  man  desires  in  subordination  to  God 
is  a  road  leading  the  imperfect  to  the  love  of  God,  according 
to  Ps.  xlviii.  19 :  He  will  praise  Thee,  when  Thou  shall  do  well 
to  him. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Human  law  persuades  men  by  means  of 
temporal  rewards  or  by  punishments  to  be  inflicted  by  men : 


Q.  99.  Art  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  112 

whereas  the  Divine  law  persuades  men  by  means  of  rewards 
or  punishments  to  be  received  from  God.  In  this  respect 
it  employs  higher  means. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  anyone  can  see,  who  reads  carefully 
the  story  of  the  Old  Testament,  the  common  weal  of  the 
people  prospered  under  the  Law  as  long  as  they  obeyed  it ; 
and  as  soon  as  they  departed  from  the  precepts  of  the  Law 
they  were  overtaken  by  many  calamities.  But  certain 
individuals,  although  they  observed  the  justice  of  the  Law, 
met  with  misfortunes, — either  because  they  had  already 
become  spiritual  (so  that  misfortune  might  withdraw  them 
all  the  more  from  attachment  to  temporal  things,  and  that 
their  virtue  might  be  tried) ; — or  because,  while  outwardly 
fulfilling  the  works  of  the  Law,  their  heart  was  altogether 
fixed  on  temporal  goods,  and  far  removed  from  God,  ac- 
cording to  Isa.  xxix.  13  (Matth.  xv.  8) :  This  people  honoureth 
Me  with  their  lips  ;  hut  their  heart  is  far  from  Me, 


QUESTION  C. 

OF  THE  MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  THE  OLD  LAW. 

(In  Twelve  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  each  kind  of  precept  of  the  Old  Law : 
and  (i)   the  moral  precepts,    (2)   the  ceremonial  precepts, 

(3)  the  judicial  precepts.  Under  the  first  head  there  are 
twelve  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  all  the  moral  precepts 
of  the  Old  Law  belong  to  the  law  of  nature  ?  (2)  Whether 
the  moral  precepts  of  the  Old  Law  are  about  the  acts  of  all 
the  virtues  ?  (3)  Whether  all  the  moral  precepts  of  the  Old 
Law  are  reducible  to  the  ten  precepts  of  the  decalogue  ? 

(4)  How  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  distinguished  from 
one  another  :  (5)  Their  number  ;  (6)  Their  order  ;  (7)  The 
manner  in  which  they  were  given;  (8)  Whether  they  are 
dispensable  ?  (9)  Whether  the  mode  of  observing  a  virtue 
comes  under  the  precept  of  the  Law  ?  (10)  Whether  the 
mode  of  charity  comes  under  the  precept  ?  (11)  The  dis- 
tinction of  other  moral  precepts.  (12)  Whether  the  moral 
precepts  of  the  Old  Law  justified  man  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  all  the  moral  precepts  of  the  old  law 
belong  to  the  law  of  nature  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  not  all  the  moral  precepts 
belong  to  the  law  of  nature.  For  it  is  written  (Ecclus. 
xvii.  9) :  Moreover  He  gave  them  instructions,  and  the  law  of 
life  for  an  inheritance.  But  instruction  is  in  contradistinc- 
tion to  the  law  of  nature ;  since  the  law  of  nature  is  not  learnt, 

11-  3  113  8 


Q.  loo.  Art.  i      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  114 

but  instilled  by  natural  instinct.     Therefore  not   all  the 
mora]  precepts  belong  to  the  natural  law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Divine  law  is  more  perfect  than  human 
law.  But  human  law  adds  certain  things  concerning  good 
morals,  to  those  that  belong  to  the  law  of  nature :  as  is  evi- 
denced by  the  fact  that  the  natural  law  is  the  same  in  all 
men,  while  these  moral  institutions  are  various  for  various 
people.  Much  more  reason  therefore  was  there  why  the 
Divine  law  should  add  to  the  law  of  nature,  ordinances 
pertaining  to  good  morals. 

Obj,  3.  Further,  just  as  natural  reason  leads  to  good 
morals  in  certain  matters,  so  does  faith:  hence  it  is  written 
(Gal.  V.  6)  that  faith  worketh  by  chanty.  But  faith  is  not 
included  in  the  law  of  nature;  since  that  which  is  of  faith 
is  above  nature.  Therefore  not  all  the  moral  precepts  of 
the  Divine  law  belong  to  the  law  of  nature. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  ii.  14)  that  the 
Gentiles,  who  have  not  the  Law,  do  by  nature  those  things  that 
are  of  the  Law  :  which  must  be  understood  of  things  per- 
taining to  good  morals.  Therefore  all  the  moral  precepts 
of  the  Law  belong  to  the  law  of  nature. 

/  answer  that.  The  moral  precepts,  distinct  from  the  cere- 
monial and  judicial  precepts,  are  about  things  pertaining 
of  their  very  nature  to  good  morals.  Now  since  human 
morals  depend  on  their  relation  to  reason,  which  is  the 
proper  principle  of  human  acts,  those  morals  are  called  good 
which  accord  with  reason,  and  those  are  called  bad  which 
are  discordant  from  reason.  And  as  every  judgment  of 
speculative  reason  proceeds  from  the  natural  knowledge  of 
hrst  principles,  so  every  judgment  of  practical  reason 
proceeds  from  principles  known  naturally,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XCIV.  AA.  2,  4)  :  from  which  principles  one  may  pro- 
ceed in  various  ways  to  judge  of  various  matters.  For 
some  matters  connected  with  human  actions  are  so  evident, 
that  after  very  little  consideration  one  is  able  at  once  to 
approve  or  disapprove  of  them  by  means  of  these  general 
first  principles:  while  some  matters  cannot  be  the  subject 
of  judgment  without  much  consideration  of    the   various 


115      MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW    Q.  loo.  Art.  i 

circumstances,  which  all  are  not  competent  to  do  care- 
fully, but  only  those  who  are  wise:  just  as  it  is  not 
possible  for  all  to  consider  the  particular  conclusions  of 
sciences,  but  only  for  those  who  are  versed  in  philosophy: 
and  lastly  there  are  some  matters  of  which  man  cannot 
judge  unless  he  be  helped  by  Divine  instruction;  such  as 
the  articles  of  faith. 

It  is  therefore  evident  that  since  the  moral  precepts  are 
about  matters  which  concern  good  morals;  and  since  good 
morals  are  those  which  are  in  accord  with  reason ;  and  since 
also  every  judgment  of  human  reason  must  needs  be  derived 
in  some  way  from  natural  reason  ;  it  follows,  of  necessity, 
that  all  the  moral  precepts  belong  to  the  law  of  nature ;  but 
not  all  in  the  same  way.  For  there  are  certain  things 
which  the  natural  reason  of  every  man,  of  its  own  accord 
and  at  once,  judges  to  be  done  or  not  to  be  done :  e.g.,  Honour 
thy  father  and  thy  mother,  and.  Thou  shalt  not  kill.  Thou  shall 
not  steal :  and  these  belong  to  the  law  of  nature  absolutely. — 
And  there  are  certain  things  which,  after  a  more  careful 
consideration,  wise  men  deem  obligatory.  Such  belong  to 
the  law  of  nature,  yet  so  that  they  need  to  be  inculcated, 
the  wiser  teaching  the  less  wise:  e.g.,  Rise  up  before  the 
hoary  head,  and  honour  the  person  of  the  aged  man,  and  the 
like. — And  there  are  some  things,  to  judge  of  which,  human 
reason  needs  Divine  instruction,  whereby  we  are  taught 
about  the  things  of  God:  e.g.,  Thou  shalt  not  make  to  thyself 
a  graven  thing,  nor  the  likeness  of  anything  ;  Thou  shalt  not 
take  the  name  of  the  Lord  thy  God  in  vain. 

This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Objections. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  moral  precepts  of  the  law  are  about 
all  the  acts  of  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  moral  precepts  of  the  Law 
are  not  about  all  the  acts  of  virtue.  For  observance  of  the 
precepts  of  the  Old  Law  is  called  justihcation,  according  to 


Q.  loo.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  116 

Ps.  cxviii.  8:  /  will  keep  Thy  justifications.  But  justification 
is  the  execution  of  justice.  Therefore  the  moral  precepts 
are  only  about  acts  of  justice. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  that  which  comes  under  a  precept  has 
the  character  of  a  duty.  But  the  character  of  duty  belongs 
to  justice  alone  and  to  none  of  the  other  virtues,  for  the 
proper  act  of  justice  consists  in  rendering  to  each  one  his  due. 
Therefore  the  precepts  of  the  moral  law  are  not  about  the 
acts  of  the  other  virtues,  but  only  about  the  acts  of  justice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  every  law  is  made  for  the  common  good, 
as  Isidore  says  (Etym.  ii.).  But  of  all  the  virtues  justice 
alone  regards  the  common  good,  as  the  Philosopher  says 
(Ethic,  v.).  Therefore  the  moral  precepts  are  only  about 
the  acts  of  justice. 

On  the  contrary,  Ambrose  says  [De  Paradiso  viii.)  that  a 
sin  is  a  transgression  of  the  Divine  law,  and  a  disobedience 
to  the  commandments  of  heaven.  But  there  are  sins  contrary 
to  all  the  acts  of  virtue.  Therefore  it  belongs  to  the  Divine 
law  to  direct  all  the  acts  of  virtue. 

/  answer  that,  Since  the  precepts  of  the  Law  are  ordained 
to  the  common  good,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2),  the 
precepts  of  the  Law  must  needs  be  diversified  according  to 
the  various  kinds  of  community:  hence  the  Philosopher 
(Polit.  iv.)  teaches  that  the  laws  which  are  made  in  a  state 
which  is  ruled  by  a  king  must  be  different  from  the  laws 
of  a  state  which  is  ruled  by  the  people,  or  by  a  few  powerful 
men  in  the  state.  Now  human  law  is  ordained  for  one 
kind  of  community,  and  the  Divine  law  for  another  kind. 
Because  human  law  is  ordained  for  the  civil  community, 
implying  mutual  duties  of  man  and  his  fellows:  and  men 
are  ordained  to  one  another  by  outward  acts,  whereby 
men  live  in  communion  with  one  another.  This  life  in 
common  of  man  with  man  pertains  to  justice,  whose  proper 
function  consists  in  directing  the  human  community. 
Wherefore  human  law  makes  precepts  only  about  acts  of 
justice;  and  if  it  commands  acts  of  other  virtues,  this  is 
only  in  so  far  as  they  assume  the  nature  of  justice,  as  the 
Philosopher  explains  [Ethic,  v.). 


117       MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW     Q.  too.  Art.  2 

But  the  community  for  which  the  Divine  law  is  ordained, 
is  that  of  men  in  relation  to  God,  either  in  this  life  or  in  the 
Ufe  to  come.  And  therefore  the  Divine  law  proposes  pre- 
cepts about  all  those  matters  whereby  men  are  well  ordered 
in  their  relations  to  God.  Now  man  is  united  to  God  by 
his  reason  or  mind,  in  which  is  God's  image.  Wherefore 
the  Divine  law  proposes  precepts  about  all  those  matters 
whereby  human  reason  is  well  ordered.  But  this  is  effected 
by  the  acts  of  all  the  virtues:  since  the  intellectual  virtues 
set  in  good  order  the  acts  of  the  reason  in  themselves :  while 
the  moral  virtues  set  in  good  order  the  acts  of  the  reason 
in  reference  to  the  interior  passions  and  exterior  actions. 
It  is  therefore  evident  that  the  Divine  law  fittingly  proposes 
precepts  about  the  acts  of  all  the  virtues :  yet  so  that  certain 
matters,  without  which  the  order  of  virtue,  which  is  the 
order  of  reason,  cannot  even  exist,  come  under  an  obligation 
of  precept;  while  other  matters,  which  pertain  to  the  well- 
being  of  perfect  virtue,  come  under  an  admonition  of  counsel. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  fulfilment  of  the  commandments  of 
the  Law,  even  of  those  which  are  about  the  acts  of  the  other 
virtues,  has  the  character  of  justification,  inasmuch  as  it 
is  just  that  man  should  obey  God:  or  again,  inasmuch  as  it  is 
just  that  all  that  belongs  to  man  should  be  subject  to  reason. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Justice  properly  so  called  regards  the  duty 
of  one  man  to  another :  but  all  the  other  virtues  regard  the 
duty  of  the  lower  powers  to  reason.  It  is  in  relation  to 
this  latter  duty  that  the  Philosopher  speaks  [Ethic,  v.)  of 
a  kind  of  metaphorical  justice. 

The  Reply  to  the  Third  Objection  is  clear  from  what  has 
been  said  about  the  different  kinds  of  community. 

Third  Article. 

whether  all  the  moral  precepts  of  the  old  law  are 
reducible  to  the  ten  precepts  of  the  decalogue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  not  all  the  moral  precepts  of 
the  Old  Law  are  reducible  to  the  ten  precepts  of  the  deca- 


Q.  loo.  Art.  3      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  118 

logue.  For  the  first  and  principal  precepts  of  the  Law  are, 
Thou  shalt  love  the  Lord  thy  God,  and,  Thou  shalt  love  thy 
neighbour,  as  stated  in  Matth.  xxii.  37,  39.  But  these  two 
are  not  contained  in  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue.  There- 
fore not  all  the  moral  precepts  are  contained  in  the  precepts 
of  the  decalogue. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  moral  precepts  are  not  reducible  to 
the  ceremonial  precepts,  but  rather  vice  versa.  But  among 
the  precepts  of  the  decalogue,  one  is  ceremonial,  viz..  Re- 
member that  thou  keep  holy  the  Sabbath-day.  Therefore  the 
moral  precepts  are  not  reducible  to  all  the  precepts  of  the 
decalogue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  moral  precepts  are  about  all  the  acts 
of  virtue.  But  among  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are 
only  such  as  regard  acts  of  justice;  as  may  be  seen  by 
going  through  them  all.  Therefore  the  precepts  of  the 
decalogue  do  not  include  all  the  moral  precepts. 

Oji  the  contrary,  The  gloss  on  Matth.  v.  11:  Blessed  are  ye 
when  they  shall  revile  you,  etc.,  says  that  Moses,  after  pro- 
pounding the  ten  precepts,  set  them  out  in  detail.  Therefore 
all  the  precepts  of  the  Law  are  so  many  parts  of  the  pre- 
cepts of  the  decalogue. 

/  answer  that,  The  precepts  of  the  decalogue  differ  from 
the  other  precepts  of  the  Law,  in  the  fact  that  God  Himself 
is  said  to  have  given  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue ;  whereas 
He  gave  the  other  precepts  to  the  people  through  Moses. 
Wherefore  the  decalogue  includes  those  precepts  the  know- 
ledge of  which  man  has  immediately  from  God.  Such 
are  those  which  with  but  slight  reflection  can  be  gathered 
at  once  from  the  first  general  principles:  and  those  also 
which  become  known  to  man  immediately  through  divinely 
infused  faith.  Consequently  two  kinds  of  precepts  are  not 
reckoned  among  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue:  viz.,  first 
general  principles,  for  they  need  no  further  promulgation 
after  being  once  imprinted  on  the  natural  reason  to  which 
they  are  self-evident;  as,  for  instance,  that  one  should  do 
evil  to  no  man,  and  other  similar  principles: — and  again 
those  which  the  careful  reflection  of  wise  men  shows  to  be 


119     MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW    Q.  loo.  Art.  3 

in  accord  with  reason;  since  the  people  receive  these  prin- 
ciples from  God,  through  being  taught  by  wise  men.  Never- 
theless both  kinds  of  precepts  are  contained  in  the  precepts 
of  the  decalogue;  yet  in  different  ways.  For  the  first 
general  principles  are  contained  in  them,  as  principles  in 
their  proximate  conclusions;  while  those  which  are  known 
through  wise  men  are  contained,  conversely,  as  conclusions 
in  their  principles. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Those  two  principles  are  the  first  general 
principles  of  the  natural  law,  and  are  self-evident  to  human 
reason,  either  through  nature  or  through  faith.  Wherefore 
all  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  referred  to  these,  as 
conclusions  to  general  principles. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  precept  of  the  Sabbath  observance  is 
moral  in  one  respect,  in  so  far  as  it  commands  man  to  give 
some  time  to  the  things  of  God,  according  to  Ps.  xlv.  it: 
Be  still  and  see  that  I  am  God.  In  this  respect  it  is  placed 
among  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  :  but  not  as  to  the 
fixing  of  the  time,  in  which  respect  it  is  a  ceremonial  pre- 
cept. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  notion  of  duty  is  not  so  patent  in  the 
other  virtues  as  it  is  in  justice.  Hence  the  precepts  about 
the  acts  of  the  other  virtues  are  not  so  well  known  to  the 
people  as  are  the  precepts  about  acts  of  justice.  Where- 
fore the  acts  of  justice  especially  come  under  the  precepts 
of  the  decalogue,  which  are  the  primary  elements  of  the 
Law. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  suitably 
distinguished  from  one  another  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue 
are  unsuitably  distinguished  from  one  another.  For  wor- 
ship is  a  virtue  distinct  from  faith.  Now  the  precepts  are 
about  acts  of  virtue.  But  that  which  is  said  at  the  begin- 
ning of  the  decalogue,  Thou  shall  not  have  strange  gods  he/ore 
Me,  belongs  to  faith:  and  that  which  is  added,  Thou  shall 


Q.  loo.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  120 

not  make  .  .  .  any  graven  thing,  etc.,  belongs  to  worship. 
Therefore  these  are  not  one  precept,  as  Augustine  says 
(Q.  LXXL  in  Exod.),  but  two. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  affirmative  precepts  in  the  Law  are 
distinct  from  the  negative  precepts;  e.g.,  Honour  thy  father 
and  thy  mother,  and.  Thou  shalt  not  kill.  But  this,  /  am  the 
Lord  thy  God,  is  affirmative :  and  that  which  follows.  Thou 
shalt  not  have  strange  gods  before  Me,  is  negative.  Therefore 
these  are  two  precepts,  and  do  not,  as  Augustine  says  [loc. 
cit),  make  one. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  vii.  7) :  /  had  not 
known  concupiscence,  if  the  Law  did  not  say  :  *  Thou  shalt 
not  covet. ^  Hence  it  seems  that  this  precept,  Thou  shalt 
not  covet,  is  one  precept;  and,  therefore,  should  not  be 
divided  into  two. 

On  the  contrary  stands  the  authority  of  Augustine  who, 
in  commenting  on  Exodus  {loc.  cit.)  distinguishes  three  pre- 
cepts as  referring  to  God,  and  seven  as  referring  to  our 
neighbour. 

/  answer  that.  The  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  differently 
divided  by  different  authorities.  For  Hesychius  when  com- 
menting on  Levit.  xxvi.  26,  Ten  women  shall  hake  your  hread 
in  one  oven,  says  that  the  precept  of  the  Sabbath-day  observ- 
ance is  not  one  of  the  ten  precepts,  because  its  observance, 
in  the  letter,  is  not  binding  for  all  time.  But  he  distinguishes 
four  precepts  pertaining  to  God,  the  first  being,  I  am  the 
Lord  thy  God  ;  the  second.  Thou  shalt  not  have  strange  gods 
hefore  Me,  (thus  also  Jerome  distinguishes  these  two  pre- 
cepts, in  his  commentary  on  Osee  x.  10,  On  thy — Vulg., 
their — two  iniquities) ;  the  third  precept  according  to  him 
is,  Thou  shalt  not  make  to  thyself  any  graven  thing  ;  and  the 
fourth,  Thou  shalt  not  take  the  name  of  the  Lord  thy  God  in 
vain.  He  states  that  there  are  six  precepts  pertaining  to 
our  neighbour ;  the  first.  Honour  thy  father  and  thy  mother  ; 
the  second.  Thou  shalt  not  kill-;  the  third.  Thou  shalt  not 
commit  adultery  ;  the  fourth,  Thou  shalt  not  steal ;  the  fifth, 
Thou  shalt  not  hear  false  witness ;  the  sixth.  Thou  shalt  not  covet. 
But,  in  the  first  place,  it  seems  unbecoming  for  the  pre- 


121      MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW     Q.  loo.  Art.  4 

cept  of  the  Sabbath-day  observance  to  be  put  among  the 
precepts  of  the  decalogue,  if  it  nowise  belonged  to  the 
decalogue.  Secondly,  because,  since  it  is  written  (Matth. 
vi.  24),  No  man  can  serve  two  masters,  the  two  statements, 
/  am  the  Lord  thy  God,  and,  Thou  shalt  not  have  strange  gods 
before  Me  seem  to  be  of  the  same  nature  and  to  form  one 
precept.  Hence  Origen  (Ho/n.  viii.  in  Exod.),  who  also  dis- 
tinguishes four  precepts  as  referring  to  God,  unites  these 
two  under  one  precept;  and  reckons  in  the  second  place, 
Thou  shalt  not  make  .  .  .  any  graven  thing  ;  as  third.  Thou 
shalt  not  take  the  name  of  the  Lord  thy  God  in  vain  ;  and  as 
fourth.  Remember  that  thou  keep  holy  the  Sabbath-day.  The 
other  six  he  reckons  in  the  same  way  as  Hesychius. 

Since,  however,  the  making  of  graven  things  or  the  like- 
ness of  anything  is  not  forbidden  except  as  to  the  point  of 
their  being  worshipped  as  gods — for  God  commanded  an 
image  of  the  Seraphim  (Vulg., — Cherubim)  to  be  made  and 
placed  in  the  tabernacle,  as  related  in  Exod.  xxv.  18 — 
Augustine  more  fittingly  unites  these  two,  Thou  shalt  not 
have  strange  gods  before  Me,  and.  Thou  shalt  not  make  .  .  . 
any  graven  thing,  into  one  precept.  Likewise  to  covet 
another's  wife,  for  the  purpose  of  carnal  knowledge,  belongs 
to  the  concupiscence  of  the  flesh;  whereas,  to  covet  other 
things,  which  are  desired  for  the  purpose  of  possession, 
belongs  to  the  concupiscence  of  the  eyes;  wherefore  Augus- 
tine reckons  as  distinct  precepts,  that  which  forbids  the 
coveting  of  another's  goods,  and  that  which  prohibits  the 
coveting  of  another's  wife.  Thus  he  distinguishes  three 
precepts  as  referring  to  God,  and  seven  as  referring  to  our 
neighbour.     And  this  is  better. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Worship  is  merely  a  declaration  of  faith: 
wherefore  the  precepts  about  worship  should  not  be  reckoned 
as  distinct  from  those  about  faith.  Nevertheless  precepts 
should  be  given  about  worship  rather  than  about  faith, 
because  the  precept  about  faith  is  presupposed  to  the  pre- 
cepts of  the  decalogue,  as  is  also  the  precept  of  charity. 
For  just  as  the  first  general  principles  of  the  natural  law 
are  self-evident  to  a  subject  having  natural  reason,  and  need 


Q.  TOO.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  122 

no  promulgation;  so  also  to  believe  in  God  is  a  first  and 
self-evident  principle  to  a  subject  possessed  of  faith :  for  he 
that  Cometh  to  God,  must  believe  that  He  is  (Heb.  xi.  6).  Hence 
it  needs  no  other  promulgation  than  the  infusion  of  faith. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  affirmative  precepts  are  distinct  from 
the  negative,  when  one  is  not  comprised  in  the  other:  thus 
that  man  should  honour  his  parents  does  not  include  that 
he  should  not  kill  another  man;  nor  does  the  latter  include 
the  former.  But  when  an  affirmative  precept  is  included 
in  a  negative,  or  vice  versa,  we  do  not  find  that  two  distinct 
precepts  are  given:  thus  there  is  not  one  precept  saying  that 
Thou  shall  not  steal,  and  another  binding  one  to  keep  another's 
property  intact,  or  to  give  it  back  to  its  owner.  In  the  same 
way  there  are  not  different  precepts  about  believing  in  God, 
and  about  not  believing  in  strange  gods. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  All  covetousness  has  one  common  ratio: 
and  therefore  the  Apostle  speaks  of  the  commandment 
about  covetousness  as  though  it  were  one.  But  because 
there  are  various  special  kinds  of  covetousness,  therefore 
Augustine  distinguishes  different  prohibitions  against  covet- 
ing: for  covetousness  differs  specifically  in  respect  of  the 
diversity  of  actions  or  things  coveted,  as  the  Philosopher 
says  (Ethic,  x.). 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  suitably 

set  forth  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue 
are  unsuitably  set  forth.  Because  sin,  as  stated  by  Ambrose 
(De  Paradiso  viii.),  is  a  transgression  of  the  Divine  law  and  a 
disobedience  to  the  commandments  of  heaven.  But  sins  are 
distinguished  according  as  man  sins  against  God,  or  his 
neighbour,  or  himself.  Since,  then,  the  decalogue  does 
not  include  any  precepts  directing  man  in  his  relations  to 
himself,  but  only  such  as  direct  him  in  his  relations  to  God 
and  himself,  it  seems  that  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue 
are  insufficiently  enumerated. 


123      MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW     Q.  loo.  Art.  5 

Obj.  2.  Further,  just  as  the  Sabbath-day  observance  per- 
tained to  the  worship  of  God,  so  also  did  the  observance  of 
other  solemnities,  and  the  offering  of  sacrifices.  But  the 
decalogue  contains  a  precept  about  the  Sabbath-day  observ- 
ance. Therefore  it  should  contain  others  also,  pertaining 
to  the  other  solemnities,  and  to  the  sacrificial  rite. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  as  sins  against  C}od  include  the  sin  of 
perjury,  so  also  do  they  include  blasphemy,  or  other  ways  of 
lying  against  the  teaching  of  God.  But  there  is  a  precept 
forbidding  perjury,  Thou  shall  not  take  the  name  of  the  Lord 
thy  God  in  vain.  Therefore  there  should  be  also  a  precept 
of  the  decalogue  forbidding  blasphemy  and  false  doctrine. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  just  as  man  has  a  natural  affection  for 
his  parents,  so  has  he  also  for  his  children.  Moreover  the 
commandment  of  charity  extends  to  all  our  neighbours. 
Now  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  ordained  unto  charity, 
according  to  i  Tim.  i.  5:  The  end  of  the  commandment  is 
charity.  Therefore  as  there  is  a  precept  referring  to  parents, 
so  should  there  have  been  some  precepts  referring  to  children 
and  other  neighbours. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  in  every  kind  of  sin,  it  is  possible  to  sin 
in  thought  or  in  deed.  But  in  some  kinds  of  sin,  namely 
in  theft  and  adultery,  the  prohibition  of  sins  of  deed,  when  it 
is  said,  Thou  shall  not  commit  adultery,  Thou  shall  not  steal, 
is  distinct  from  the  prohibition  of  the  sin  of  thought,  when 
it  is  said,  Thou  shall  not  covet  thy  neighbour's  goods,  and. 
Thou  shall  not  covet  thy  neighbour"* s  wife.  Therefore  the  same 
should  have  been  done  in  regard  to  the  sins  of  homicide 
and  false  witness. 

Obj.  6.  Further,  just  as  sin  happens  through  disorder  of 
the  concupiscible  faculty,  so  does  it  arise  through  disorder 
of  the  irascible  part.  But  some  precepts  forbid  inordinate 
concupiscence,  when  it  is  said.  Thou  shall  not  covet.  There- 
fore the  decalogue  should  have  included  some  precepts 
forbidding  the  disorders  of  the  irascible  faculty.  There- 
fore it  seems  that  the  ten  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are 
unfittingly  emmierated. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  (Deut.  iv.  13) :  He  shewed  you 


Q.  loo.  Art.  5      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  124 

His  covenant,  which  He  commanded  you  to  do,  and  the  ten 
words  that  He  wrote  in  two  tables  of  stone. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  2),  just  as  the  precepts 
of  human  law  direct  man  in  his  relations  to  the  human 
community,  so  the  precepts  of  the  Divine  law  direct  man  in 
his  relations  to  a  community  or  commonwealth  of  men 
under  God.  Now  in  order  that  any  man  may  dwell  aright 
in  a  community,  two  things  are  required:  the  first  is  that 
he  behave  well  to  the  head  of  the  community;  the  other 
is  that  he  behave  well  to  those  who  are  his  fellows  and 
partners  in  the  community.  It  is  therefore  necessary  that 
the  Divine  law  should  contain  in  the  first  place  precepts 
ordering  man  in  his  relations  to  God;  and  in  the  second  place, 
other  precepts  ordering  man  in  his  relations  to  other  men 
who  are  his  neighbours  and  live  with  him  under  God. 

Now  man  owes  three  things  to  the  head  of  the  community : 
first,  fidelity;  secondly,  reverence;  thirdly,  service.  Fidelity 
to  his  master  consists  in  his  not  giving  sovereign  honour  to 
another:  and  this  is  the  sense  of  the  first  commandment, 
in  the  words,  Thou  shalt  not  have  strange  gods. — Reverence 
to  his  master  requires  that  he  should  do  nothing  injurious 
to  him:  and  this  is  conveyed  by  the  second  commandment. 
Thou  shalt  not  take  the  name  of  the  Lord  thy  God  in  vain. — 
Service  is  due  to  the  master  in  return  for  the  benefits  which 
his  subjects  receive  from  him:  and  to  this  belongs  the  third 
commandment  of  the  sanctification  of  the  Sabbath  in 
memory  of  the  creation  of  all  things. 

To  his  neighbours  a  man  behaves  himself  well  both  in 
particular  and  in  general.  In  particular,  as  to  those  to  whom 
he  is  indebted,  by  paying  his  debts :  and  in  this  sense  is  to 
be  taken  the  commandment  about  honouring  one's  parents. 
— In  general,  as  to  all  men,  by  doing  harm  to  none,  either 
by  deed,  or  by  word,  or  by  thought.  By  deed,  harm  is 
done  to  one's  neighbour, — sometimes  in  his  person,  i.e.,  as 
to  his  personal  existence ;  and  this  is  forbidden  by  the  words, 
Thou  shalt  not  kill : — sometimes  in  a  person  united  to  him, 
as  to  the  propagation  of  offspring;  and  this  is  prohibited 
by  the  words.  Thou  shalt  not  commit  adultery  : — sometimes 


125      MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW      Q.  icx).Art.  5 

in  his  possessions,  which  are  directed  to  both  the  aforesaid; 
and  with  regard  to  this  it  is  said,  Thou  shall  not  steal. — 
Harm  done  by  word  is  forbidden  when  it  is  said.  Thou  shall 
not  bear  false  witness  against  thy  neighbour  : — harm  done 
by  thought  is  forbidden  in  the  words.  Thou  shall  not  covet. 

The  three  precepts  that  direct  man  in  his  behaviour 
towards  God  may  also  be  differentiated  in  this  same  way. 
For  the  first  refers  to  deeds ;  wherefore  it  is  said.  Thou  shall 
not  make  .  .  .  a  graven  thing  :  the  second,  to  words ;  wherefore 
it  is  said,  Thou  shall  not  lake  the  name  of  the  Lord  thy  God 
in  vain  :  the  third,  to  thoughts;  because  the  sanctification 
of  the  Sabbath,  as  the  subject  of  a  moral  precept,  requires 
repose  of  the  heart  in  God. — Or,  according  to  Augustine 
{In  Ps.  xxxii. :  Serm.  i),  by  the  first  commandment  we 
reverence  the  unity  of  the  First  Principle;  by  the  second, 
the  Divine  truth;  by  the  third.  His  goodness  whereby  we 
are  sanctified,  and  wherein  we  rest  as  in  our  last  end. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  This  objection  may  be  answered  in  two 
ways.  First,  because  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  can  be 
reduced  to  the  precepts  of  charity.  Now  there  was  need  for 
man  to  receive  a  precept  about  loving  God  and  his  neigh- 
bour, because  in  this  respect  the  natural  law  had  become 
obscured  on  account  of  sin :  but  not  about  the  duty  of  loving 
oneself,  because  in  this  respect  the  natural  law  retained 
its  vigour:  or  again,  because  love  of  oneself  is  contained 
in  the  love  of  God  and  of  one's  neighbour :  since  true  self- 
love  consists  in  directing  oneself  to  God.  And  for  this 
reason  the  decalogue  includes  those  precepts  only  which 
refer  to  our  neighbour  and  to  God. 

Secondly,  it  may  be  answered  that  the  precepts  of  the 
decalogue  are  those  which  the  people  received  from  God 
immediately;  wherefore  it  is  written  (Deut.  x.  4):  He  wrote 
in  the  tables,  according  as  He  had  written  before,  the  ten  words, 
which  the  Lord  spoke  to  you.  Hence  the  precepts  of  the 
decalogue  need  to  be  such  as  the  people  can  understand  at 
once.  Now  a  precept  implies  the  notion  of  duty.  But  it 
is  easy  for  a  man,  especially  for  a  believer,  to  understand 
that,  of  necessity,  he  owes  certain  duties  to  God  and  to  his 


Q.  loo.  Art.  5      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  126 

neighbour.  But  that,  in  matters  which  regard  himself  and 
not  another,  man  has,  of  necessity,  certain  duties  to  himself, 
is  not  so  evident:  for,  at  the  first  glance,  it  seems  that  every- 
one is  free  in  matters  that  concern  himself.  And  therefore 
the  precepts  which  prohibit  disorders  of  a  man  with  regard 
to  himself,  reach  the  people  through  the  instruction  of  men 
who  are  versed  in  such  matters ;  and,  consequently,  they  are 
not  contained  in  the  decalogue. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  All  the  solemnities  of  the  Old  Law  were 
instituted  in  celebration  of  some  Divine  favour,  either  in 
memory  of  past  favours,  or  in  sign  of  some  favour  to  come : 
in  like  manner  all  the  sacrifices  were  offered  up  with  the 
same  purpose.  Now  of  all  the  Divine  favours  to  be  com- 
memorated the  chief  was  that  of  the  Creation,  which  was 
called  to  mind  by  the  sanctification  of  the  Sabbath;  where- 
fore the  reason  for  this  precept  is  given  in  Exod.  xx.  11: 
In  six  days  the  Lord  made  heaven  and  earth,  etc.  And  of  all 
future  blessings,  the  chief  and  final  was  the  repose  of  the 
mind  in  God,  either,  in  the  present  life,  by  grace,  or,  in  the 
future  life,  by  glory;  which  repose  was  also  foreshadowed 
in  the  Sabbath-day  observance:  wherefore  it  is  written 
(Isa.  Iviii.  13) :  //  thou  turn  away  thy  foot  from  the  Sabbath, 
from  doing  thy  own  will  in  My  holy  day,  and  call  the  Sabbath 
delightful,  and  the  holy  of  the  Lord  glorious.  Because  these 
favours  first  and  chiefly  are  borne  in  mind  by  men,  especi- 
ally by  the  faithful. — But  other  solemnities  were  celebrated 
on  account  of  certain  particular  favours  temporal  and 
transitory,  such  as  the  celebration  of  the  Passover  in  memory 
of  the  past  favour  of  the  delivery  from  Egypt,  and  as  a  sign 
of  the  future  Passion  of  Christ,  which  though  temporal  and 
transitory,  brought  us  to  the  repose  of  the  spiritual  Sabbath. 
Consequently,  the  Sabbath  alone,  and  none  of  the  other 
solemnities  and  sacrifices,  is  mentioned  in  the  precepts  of 
the  decalogue. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  the  Apostle  says  (Heb.  vi.  16),  men  swear 
by  one  greater  than  themselves  ;  and  an  oath  for  confirmation 
is  the  end  of  all  their  controversy.  Hence,  since  oaths  are 
common  to  all,  inordinate  swearing  is  the  matter  of  a  special 


127      MORAL  PRECEPTS  OE  OLD  LAW    Q.  loo.  Art.  5 

prohibition  by  a  precept  of  the  decalogue.  According  to 
one  interpretation,  however,  the  words.  Thou  shall  not  lake 
the  name  of  the  Lord  thy  God  in  vain,  are  a  prohibition  of  false 
doctrine,  for  one  gloss  expounds  them  thus:  Thou  shall  not 
say  that  Christ  is  a  creature. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  That  a  man  should  not  do  harm  to  anyone 
is  an  immediate  dictate  of  his  natural  reason:  and  therefore 
the  precepts  that  forbid  the  doing  of  harm  are  binding  on 
all  men.  But  it  is  not  an  immediate  dictate  of  natural 
reason  that  a  man  should  do  one  thing  in  return  for  another, 
unless  he  happen  to  be  indebted  to  someone.  Now  a  son's 
debt  to  his  father  is  so  evident  that  one  cannot  get  away 
from  it  by  denying  it:  since  the  father  is  the  principle  of 
generation  and  being,  and  also  of  upbringing  and  teaching. 
Wherefore  the  decalogue  does  not  prescribe  deeds  of  kind- 
ness or  service  to  be  done  to  anyone  except  to  one's  parents. 
On  the  other  hand  parents  do  not  seem  to  be  indebted  to 
their  children  for  any  favours  received,  but  rather  the  reverse 
is  the  case. — Again,  a  child  is  a  part  of  his  father;  and 
parents  love  their  children  as  being  a  part  of  themselves,  as 
the  Philosopher  states  (Ethic,  viii.).  Hence,  just  as  the 
decalogue  contains  no  ordinance  as  to  man's  behaviour 
towards  himself,  so,  for  the  same  reason,  it  includes  no 
precept  about  loving  one's  children. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  The  pleasure  of  adultery  and  the  usefulness 
of  wealth,  in  so  far  as  they  have  the  character  of  pleasurable 
or  useful  good,  are,  of  themselves,  objects  of  appetite:  and 
for  this  reason  they  needed  to  be  forbidden  not  only  in  the 
deed  but  also  in  the  desire.  But  murder  and  falsehood 
are,  of  themselves,  objects  of  repulsion  (since  it  is  natural 
for  man  to  love  his  neighbour  and  the  truth) :  and  are 
desired  only  for  the  sake  of  something  else.  Consequently 
with  regard  to  sins  of  murder  and  false  witness,  it  was 
necessary  to  proscribe,  not  sins  of  thought,  but  only  sins 
of  deed. 

Reply  Obj.  6.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXV.,  A.  i),  all  the 
passions  of  the  irascible  faculty  arise  from  the  passions  of 
the    concupiscible    part.     Hence,    as   the    precepts   of    the 


Q.  loo.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  128 

decalogue  arc,  as  it  were,  the  iirst  elements  of  the  Law, 
there  was  no  need  for  mention  of  the  irascible  passions,  but 
only  of  the  concupiscible  passions. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  the  ten  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  set 

in  proper  order  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  ten  precepts  of  the  deca- 
logue are  not  set  in  proper  order.  Because  love  of  one's 
neighbour  is  seemingly  previous  to  love  of  God,  since  our 
neighbour  is  better  known  to  us  than  God  is;  according  to 
I  John  iv.  20:  He  that  loveth  not  his  brother,  whom  he  seeth, 
how  can  he  love  God,  Whom  he  seeth  not  ?  But  the  fkst  three 
precepts  belong  to  the  love  of  God,  while  the  other  seven 
pertain  to  the  love  of  our  neighbour.  Therefore  the  pre- 
cepts of  the  decalogue  are  not  set  in  proper  order. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  acts  of  virtue  are  prescribed  by  the 
affirmative  precepts,  and  acts  of  vice  are  forbidden  by  the 
negative  precepts.  But  according  to  Boethius  in  his  com- 
mentary on  the  Predicaments,  vices  should  be  uprooted 
before  virtues  are  sown.  Therefore  among  the  precepts 
concerning  our  neighbour,  the  negative  precepts  should  have 
preceded  the  affirmative. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  precepts  of  the  Law  are  about  men's 
actions.  But  actions  of  thought  precede  actions  of  word  or 
outward  deed.  Therefore  the  precepts  about  not  coveting, 
which  regard  our  thoughts,  are  unsuitably  placed  last  in 
order. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  xiii.  i) :  The  things 
that  are  of  God,  are  well  ordered  (Vulg., — Those  that  are,  are 
ordained  of  God).  But  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  were 
given  immediately  by  God,  as  stated  above  (A.  3).  There- 
fore they  are  arranged  in  becoming  order. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (AA.  3,  5  ad  i),  the  pre- 
cepts of  the  decalogue  are  such  as  the  mind  of  man  is  ready 
to  grasp  at  once.      Now  it  is  evident  that  a  thing  is  so  much 


129      MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW     Q.  loo.  Art.  6 

the  more  easily  grasped  by  the  reason,  as  its  contrary  is  more 
grievous  and  repugnant  to  reason.  Moreover  it  is  clear, 
since  the  order  of  reason  begins  with  the  end,  that,  for  a 
man  to  be  inordinately  disposed  towards  his  end,  is  su- 
premely contrary  to  reason.  Now  the  end  of  human  life 
and  society  is  God.  Consequently  it  was  necessary  for  the 
precepts  of  the  decalogue,  first  of  all,  to  direct  man  to  God; 
since  the  contrary  to  this  is  most  grievous.  Thus  also,  in 
an  army,  which  is  ordained  to  the  commander  as  to  its 
end,  it  is  requisite  first  that  the  soldier  should  be  subject 
to  the  commander,  and  the  opposite  of  this  is  most 
grievous;  and  secondly  it  is  requisite  that  he  should  be  in 
co-ordination  with  the  other  soldiers. 

Now  among  those  things  whereby  we  are  ordained  to  God, 
the  first  is  that  man  should  be  subjected  to  Him  faithfully, 
by  having  nothing  in  common  with  His  enemies.  The 
second  is  that  he  should  show  Him  reverence:  the  third 
that  he  should  offer  Him  his  service.  Thus,  in  an  army,  it 
is  a  greater  sin  for  a  soldier  to  act  treacherously  and  make  a 
compact  with  the  foe,  than  to  be  insolent  to  his  commander : 
and  this  last  is  more  grievous  than  if  he  be  found  wanting 
in  some  point  of  service  to  him. 

As  to  the  precepts  that  direct  man  in  his  behaviour  to- 
wards his  neighbour,  it  is  evident  that  it  is  more  repugnant 
to  reason,  and  a  more  grievous  sin,  if  man  does  not  observe 
the  due  order  as  to  those  persons  to  whom  he  is  most  in- 
debted. Consequently,  among  those  precepts  that  direct 
man  in  his  relations  to  his  neighbour,  the  first  place  is  given 
to  that  one  which  regards  his  parents.  Among  the 
other  precepts  we  again  find  the  order  to  be  according  to 
the  gravity  of  sin.  For  it  is  more  grave  and  more  repugnant 
to  reason,  to  sin  by  deed  than  by  word;  and  by  word  than  by 
thought.  And  among  sins  of  deed,  murder  which  destroys 
life  in  one  already  living  is  more  grievous  than  adultery, 
which  imperils  the  life  of  the  unborn  child;  and  adultery 
is  more  grave  than  theft,  which  regards  external  goods. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Although  our  neighbour  is  better  known  than 
God  by  the  way  of  the  senses,  nevertheless  the  love  of  God 

"•  3  9 


Q.  TOO.  Art.  6      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  130 

is  the  reason  for  the  love  of  our  neighbour,  as  shall  be  de- 
clared later  on  (II.-IL,  Q.  XXV.,  A.  i;  Q.  XXVL,  A.  2). 
Hence  the  precepts  ordaining  man  to  God  demanded 
precedence  of  the  others. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Just  as  God  is  the  universal  principle  of 
being  in  respect  of  all  things,  so  is  a  father  a  principle  of 
being  in  respect  of  his  son.  Therefore  the  precept  regarding 
parents  was  fittingly  placed  after  the  precepts  regarding  God. 
This  argument  holds  in  respect  of  affirmative  and  negative 
precepts  about  the  same  kind  of  deed:  although  even  then 
it  is  not  altogether  cogent.  For  although  in  the  order  of 
execution,  vices  should  be  uprooted  before  virtues  are  sown, 
according  to  Ps.  xxxiii.  15:  Turn  away  from  evil,  and  do 
good,  and  Isa.  i.  16,  17 :  Cease  to  do  perversely  ;  learn  to  do 
well ;  yet,  in  the  order  of  knowledge,  virtue  precedes  vice, 
because  the  crooked  line  is  known  by  the  straight  (De  Anima  i.) : 
and  by  the  law  is  the  knowledge  of  sin  (Rom.  iii.  20).  Where- 
fore the  affirmative  precept  demanded  the  first  place. 
However,  this  is  not  the  reason  for  the  order,  but  that  which 
is  given  above.  Because  in  the  precepts  regarding  God, 
which  belong  to  the  first  table,  an  affirmative  precept  is 
placed  last,  since  its  transgression  implies  a  less  grievous  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Although  sin  of  thought  stands  first  in  the 
order  of  execution,  yet  its  prohibition  holds  a  later  position 
in  the  order  of  reason. 


Seventh  Article. 

whether  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  suitably 

formulated  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue 
are  unsuitably  formulated.  Because  the  affirmative  pre- 
cepts direct  man  to  acts  of  virtue,  while  the  negative  pre- 
cepts withdraw  him  from  acts  of  vice.  But  in  every  matter 
there  are  virtues  and  vices  opposed  to  one  another.  There- 
fore in  whatever  matter  there  is  an  ordinance  of  a  precept 


131      MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW    Q.  loo.  Art.  7 

of  the  decalogue,  there  should  have  been  an  affirmative 
and  a  negative  precept.  Therefore  it  was  unfitting  that 
affirmative  precepts  should  be  framed  in  some  matters, 
and  negative  precepts  in  others. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Isidore  says  [Etym.  ii.)  that  every  law  is 
based  on  reason.  But  all  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue 
belong  to  the  Divine  law.  Therefore  the  reason  should 
have  been  pointed  out  in  each  precept,  and  not  only  in  the 
first  and  third. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  by  observing  the  precepts  man  deserves 
to  be  rewarded  by  God.  But  the  Divine  promises  concern 
the  rewards  of  the  precepts.  Therefore  the  promise  should 
have  been  included  in  each  precept,  and  not  only  in  the 
second  and  fourth. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  the  Old  Law  is  called  the  law  of  fear,  in 
so  far  as  it  induced  men  to  observe  the  precepts,  by  means 
of  the  threat  of  punishments.  But  all  the  precepts  of  the 
decalogue  belong  to  the  Old  Law.  Therefore  a  threat  of 
punishment  should  have  been  included  in  each,  and  not 
only  in  the  first  and  second. 

Ohj.  5.  Further,  all  the  commandments  of  God  should 
be  retained  in  the  memory:  for  it  is  written  (Pro v.  iii.  3): 
Write  them  in  the  tahles  of  thy  heart.  Therefore  it  was  not 
fitting  that  mention  of  the  memory  should  be  made  in  the 
third  commandment  only.  Consequently  it  seems  that  the 
precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  unsuitably  formulated. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Wis.  xi.  21)  that  God  made 
all  things,  in  measure,  number,  and  weight.  Much  more 
therefore  did  He  observe  a  suitable  manner  in  formulating 
His  Law. 

/  answer  that,  The  highest  wisdom  is  contained  in  the 
precepts  of  the  Divine  law:  wherefore  it  is  written  (Deut. 
iv.  6) :  This  is  your  wisdom  and  understanding  in  the  sight  of 
nations  Now  it  belongs  to  wisdom  to  arrange  all  things 
in  due  manner  and  order.  Therefore  it  must  be  evident 
that  the  precepts  of  the  Law  are  suitably  set  forth. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Affumation  of  one  thing  always  leads  to 
the  denial  of  its  opposite:  but  the  denial  of  one  opposite 


Q.  loo.  Art.  7      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  132 

does  not  always  lead  to  the  affirmation  of  the  other.  For  it 
follows  that  if  a  thing  is  white,  it  is  not  black:  but  it  does 
not  follow  that  if  it  is  not  black,  it  is  white :  because  negation 
extends  further  than  affirmation.  And  hence  too,  that  one 
ought  not  to  do  harm  to  another,  which  pertains  to  the 
negative  precepts,  extends  to  more  persons,  as  a  primary 
dictate  of  reason,  than  that  one  ought  to  do  someone  a 
service  or  kindness.  Nevertheless  it  is  a  primary  dictate 
of  reason  that  man  is  a  debtor  in  the  point  of  rendering  a 
service  or  kindness  to  those  from  whom  he  has  received 
kindness,  if  he  has  not  yet  repaid  the  debt.  Now  there  are 
two  whose  favours  no  man  can  sufficiently  repay,  viz., 
God  and  man's  father,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  viii.  Therefore 
it  is  that  there  are  only  two  affirmative  precepts;  one 
about  the  honour  due  to  parents,  the  other  about  the  cele- 
bration of  the  Sabbath  in  memory  of  the  Divine  favour. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  reasons  for  the  purely  moral  precepts 
are  manifest;  hence  there  was  no  need  to  add  the  reason. 
But  some  of  the  precepts  include  ceremonial  matter,  or  a 
determination  of  a  general  moral  precept  ;  thus  the  first 
precept  includes  the  determination.  Thou  shall  not  make  a 
graven  thing  ;  and  in  the  third  precept  the  Sabbath-day  is 
fixed.  Consequently  there  was  need  to  state  the  reason  in 
each  case. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Generally  speaking  men  direct  their  actions 
to  some  point  of  utility.  Consequently  in  those  precepts 
in  which  it  seemed  that  there  would  be  no  useful  result, 
or  that  some  utility  might  be  hindered,  it  was  necessary 
to  add  a  promise  of  reward.  And  since  parents  are  already 
on  the  way  to  depart  from  us,  no  benefit  is  expected  from 
them :  wherefore  a  promise  of  reward  is  added  to  the  precept 
about  honouring  one's  parents.  The  same  applies  to  the 
precept  forbidding  idolatry:  since  thereby  it  seemed  that 
men  were  hindered  from  receiving  the  apparent  benefit 
which  they  think  they  can  get  by  entering  into  a  compact 
with  the  demons. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  Punishments  are  necessary  against  those 
who  are  prone  to  evil,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  x.     Wherefore 


133      MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW     Q.  ,00.  Art.  8 

a  threat  of  punishment  is  only  affixed  to  those  precepts  of 
the  law  which  forbade  evils  to  which  men  were  prone. 
Now  men  were  prone  to  idolatry  by  reason  of  the  general 
custom  of  the  nations.  Likewise  men  are  prone  to  perjury 
on  account  of  the  frequent  use  of  oaths.  Hence  it  is  that 
a  threat  is  affixed  to  the  first  two  precepts. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  The  commandment  about  the  Sabbath  was 
made  in  memory  of  a  past  blessing.  Wherefore  special 
mention  of  the  memory  is  made  therein. — Or  again,  the 
commandment  about  the  Sabbath  has  a  determination 
affixed  to  it  that  does  not  belong  to  the  natural  law,  where- 
fore this  precept  needed  a  special  admonition. 

Eighth  Article. 

whether  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are 

dispensable  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue 
are  dispensable.  For  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  belong 
to  the  natural  law.  But  the  natural  law  fails  in  some  cases 
and  is  changeable,  like  human  nature,  as  the  Philosopher 
says  [Ethic,  v.).  Now  the  failure  of  law  to  apply  in  certain 
particular  cases  is  a  reason  for  dispensation,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XCVL,  A.  6;  Q.  XCVIL,  A.  4).  Therefore  a  dispensa- 
tion can  be  granted  in  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  man  stands  in  the  same  relation  to  human 
law  as  God  does  to  Divine  law.  But  man  can  dispense 
with  the  precepts  of  a  law  made  by  man.  Therefore,  since 
the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  arc  ordained  by  God,  it  seems 
that  God  can  dispense  with  them.  Now  our  superiors  are 
God's  vicegerents  on  earth;  for  the  Apostle  says  (2  Cor. 
ii.  10) :  For  what  I  have  pardoned,  if  I  have  pardoned  any- 
thing, for  your  sakes  have  I  done  it  in  the  person  of  Christ, 
Therefore  superiors  can  dispense  with  the  precepts  of  the 
decalogue. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  among  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  is 
one  forbidding  murder.     But  it  seems  that  a  dispensation 


Q.  loo.  Art.  8      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  134 

is  given  by  men  in  this  precept :  for  instance,  when  according 
to  the  prescription  of  human  law,  such  as  evil-doers  or 
enemies  are  lawfully  slain.  Therefore  the  precepts  of  the 
decalogue  are  dispensable. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  the  observance  of  the  Sabbath  is  ordained 
by  a  precept  of  the  decalogue.  But  a  dispensation  was 
granted  in  this  precept;  for  it  is  written  (i  Machab.  ii.  4): 
And  they  determined  in  that  day,  saying  :  V/hosoever  shall  come 
up  to  fight  against  us  on  the  Sabbath-day,  we  will  fight  against 
him.    Therefore  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  dispensable. 

On  the  contrary  are  the  words  of  Isa.  xxiv.  5,  where  some 
are  reproved  for  that  they  have  changed  the  ordinance,  they 
have  broken  the  everlasting  covenant ;  which,  seemingly,  apply 
principally  to  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue.  Therefore  the 
precepts  of  the  decalogue  cannot  be  changed  by  dispensation. 

/  answer  that,  Ks>  stated  above  [loc.  cit.  cf.  Obj.  i),  pre- 
cepts admit  of  dispensation,  when  there  occurs  a  particular 
case  in  which,  if  the  letter  of  the  law  be  observed,  the  inten- 
tion of  the  lawgiver  is  frustrated.  Now  the  intention  of 
every  lawgiver  is  directed  first  and  chiefly  to  the  common 
good;  secondly,  to  the  order  of  justice  and  virtue,  whereby 
the  common  good  is  preserved  and  attained.  If  therefore 
there  be  any  precepts  which  contain  the  very  preservation 
of  the  common  good,  or  the  very  order  of  justice  and  virtue, 
such  precepts  contain  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver,  and 
therefore  are  indispensable.  For  instance,  if  in  some  com- 
munity a  law  were  enacted,  such  as  this, — that  no  man 
should  work  for  the  destruction  of  the  commonwealth,  or 
betray  the  state  to  its  enemies,  or  that  no  man  should  do 
anything  unjust  or  evil,  such  precepts  would  not  admit  of 
dispensation.  But  if  other  precepts  were  enacted,  subordi- 
nate to  the  above,  and  determining  certain  special  modes  of 
procedure,  these  latter  precepts  would  admit  of  dispensa- 
tion, in  so  far  as  the  omission  of  these  precepts  in  certain  cases 
would  not  be  prejudicial  to  the  former  precepts  which  con- 
tain the  intention  of  the  lawgiver.  For  instance  if,  for  the 
safeguarding  of  the  commonwealth,  it  were  enacted  in  some 
city  that  from  each  ward  some  men  should  keep  watch  as 


135      MORAL  PRECEPTS  OE  OLD  LAW     Q.  loo.  Art.  S 

sentries  in  case  of  siege,  some  might  be  dispensed  from  this 
on  account  of  some  greater  utihty. 

Now  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  contain  the  very  in- 
tention of  the  lawgiver,  who  is  God.  For  the  precepts  of 
the  lirst  table,  which  direct  us  to  God,  contain  the  very  order 
to  the  common  and  final  good,  which  is  God;  while  the 
precepts  of  the  second  table  contain  the  order  of  justice 
to  be  observed  among  men,  that  nothing  undue  be  done  to 
anyone,  and  that  each  one  be  given  his  due ;  for  it  is  in  this 
sense  that  we  are  to  take  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue. 
Consequently  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  admit  of  no 
dispensation  whatever. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  Philosopher  is  not  speaking  of  the 
natural  law  which  contains  the  very  order  of  justice:  for 
it  is  a  never-failing  principle  that  justice  should  be  preserved. 
But  he  is  speaking  in  reference  to  certain  fixed  modes  of 
observing  justice,  which  fail  to  apply  in  certain  cases. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  the  Apostle  says  (2  Tim.  ii.  13),  God 
CO ntinueth  faithful,  He  cannot  deny  Himself.  But  He  would 
deny  Himself  if  He  were  to  do  away  with  the  very  order 
of  His  own  justice,  since  He  is  justice  itself.  Wherefore 
God  cannot  dispense  a  man  so  that  it  be  lawful  for  him 
not  to  direct  himself  to  God,  or  not  to  be  subject  to  His 
justice,  even  in  those  matters  in  which  men  are  directed  to 
one  another. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  slaying  of  a  man  is  forbidden  in  the 
decalogue,  in  so  far  as  it  bears  the  character  of  something 
undue :  for  in  this  sense  the  precept  contains  the  very  essence 
of  justice.  Human  law  cannot  make  it  lawful  for  a  man  to 
be  slain  unduly.  But  it  is  not  undue  for  evil-doers  or  foes 
of  the  common  weal  to  be  slain:  hence  this  is  not  contrary 
to  the  precept  of  the  decalogue;  and  such  a  kilUng  is  no 
murder  as  forbidden  by  that  precept,  as  Augustine  observes 
[De  Lib.  Arb.  i.). — In  like  manner  when  a  man's  property 
is  taken  from  him,  if  it  be  due  that  he  should  lose  it,  this 
is  not  theft  or  robbery  as  forbidden  by  the  decalogue. 

Consequently  when  the  children  of  Israel,  by  God's  com- 
mand, took  away  the  spoils  of  the  Egyptians,  this  was  not 


Q.  loo.  Art.  8     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  136 

theft;  since  it  was  due  to  them  by  the  sentence  of  God. — 
Likewise  when  Abraham  consented  to  slay  his  son,  he  did 
not  consent  to  murder,  because  his  son  was  due  to  be  slain 
by  the  command  of  God,  Who  is  Lord  of  life  and  death: 
for  He  it  is  Who  inflicts  the  punishment  of  death  on  all  men, 
both  godly  and  ungodly,  on  account  of  the  sin  of  our  flrst 
parent,  and  if  a  man  be  the  executor  of  that  sentence  by 
Divine  authority,  he  will  be  no  murderer  any  more  than  God 
would  be. — Again  Osee,  by  taking  unto  himself  a  wife  of 
fornications,  or  an  adulterous  woman,  was  not  guilty  either 
of  adultery  or  of  fornication:  because  he  took  unto  himself 
one  who  was  his  by  command  of  God,  Who  is  the  Author 
of  the  institution  of  marriage. 

Accordingly,  therefore,  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue, 
as  to  the  essence  of  justice  which  they  contain,  are  un- 
changeable: but  as  to  any  determination  by  application 
to  individual  actions, — for  instance  that  this  or  that  be 
murder,  theft,  or  adultery,  or  not — in  this  point  they  admit 
of  change;  sometimes  by  Divine  authority  alone,  namely, 
in  such  matters  as  are  exclusively  of  Divine  institution, 
as  marriage  and  the  like;  sometimes  also  by  human  au- 
thority, namely  in  such  matters  as  are  subject  to  human 
"N  jurisdiction:  for  in  this  respect  men  stand  in  the  place  of 
God:  and  yet  not  in  all  respects. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  This  determination  was  an  interpretation 
rather  than  a  dispensation.  For  a  man  is  not  taken  to 
break  the  Sabbath,  if  he  does  something  necessary  for  human 
welfare ;  as  Our  Lord  proves  (Matth.  xii.  3  seq.) . 

Ninth  Article. 

whether  the  mode  of  virtue  falls  under  the  precept 

of  the  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Ninth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  mode  of  virtue  falls  under 
the  precept  of  the  law.  For  the  mode  of  virtue  is  that 
deeds  of  justice  should  be  done  justly,  that  deeds  of  forti- 
tude should  be  done  bravely,  and  in  like  manner  as  to  the 


137      MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW    Q.  ,00.  Art.  9 

other  virtues.  But  it  is  commanded  (Deut.  xvi.  20)  that 
thou  shall  follow  justly  after  that  which  is  just.  Therefore 
the  mode  of  virtue  falls  under  the  precept. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  that  which  belongs  to  the  intention  of 
the  lawgiver  comes  chiefly  under  the  precept.  But  the 
intention  of  the  lawgiver  is  directed  chiefly  to  make  men 
virtuous,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  ii. :  and  it  belongs  to  a  virtuous 
man  to  act  virtuously.  Therefore  the  mode  of  virtue  falls 
under  the  precept. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  mode  of  virtue  seems  to  consist 
properly  in  working  willingly  and  with  pleasure.  But  this 
falls  under  a  precept  of  the  Divine  law,  for  it  is  written  (Ps. 
xcix.  2) :  Serve  ye  the  Lord  with  gladness ;  and  (2  Cor.  ix.  7) : 
Not  with  sadness  or  necessity  :  for  God  loveth  a  cheerful  giver; 
whereupon  the  gloss  says:  Whatever  ye  do,  do  gladly ;  and 
then  you  will  do  it  well ;  whereas  if  you  do  it  sorrowfully ,  it 
is  done  in  thee,  not  by  thee.  Therefore  the  mode  of  virtue 
falls  under  the  precept  of  the  law. 

On  the  contrary,  No  man  can  act  as  a  virtuous  man  acts 
unless  he  has  the  habit  of  virtue,  as  the  Philosopher  ex- 
plains {Ethic,  ii.  ;  v.).  Now  whoever  transgresses  a  precept 
of  the  law,  deserves  to  be  punished.  Hence  it  would  follow 
that  a  man  who  has  not  the  habit  of  virtue,  would  deserve 
to  be  punished,  whatever  he  does.  But  this  is  contrary  to 
the  intention  of  the  law,  which  aims  at  leading  man  to  virtue, 
by  habituating  him  to  good  works.  Therefore  the  mode  of 
virtue  does  not  fall  under  the  precept. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  3  ^i  2),  a  pre- 
cept of  law  has  compulsory  power.  Hence  that  on  which 
the  compulsion  of  the  law  is  brought  to  bear,  falls  directly 
under  the  precept  of  the  law.  Now  the  law  compels  through 
fear  of  punishment,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  x.,  because  that 
properly  falls  under  the  precept  of  the  law,  for  which  the 
penalty  of  the  law  is  inflicted.  But  Divine  law  and  human 
law  are  differently  situated  as  to  the  appointment  of 
penalties;  since  the  penalty  of  the  law  is  inflicted  only  for 
those  things  which  come  under  the  judgment  of  the  law- 
giver: for  the  law  punishes  in  accordance  with  the  verdict 


Q.  TOO.  Art.  9     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  138 

given.  Now  man,  the  framer  of  human  law,  is  competent 
to  judge  only  of  outward  acts;  because  man  seeth  those  things 
that  appear,  according  to  i  Kings  xvi.  7:  while  God  alone, 
the  framer  of  the  Divine  law,  is  competent  to  judge  of  the 
inward  movements  of  wills,  according  to  Ps.  vii.  10:  The 
searcher  of  hearts  and  reins  is  God. 

Accordingly,  therefore,  we  must  say  that  the  mode  of 
virtue  is  in  some  sort  regarded  both  by  human  and  by  Divine 
law;  in  some  respect  it  is  regarded  by  the  Divine,  but  not  by 
the  human  law;  and  in  another  way,  it  is  regarded  neither 
by  the  human  nor  by  the  Divine  law.  Now  the  mode  of 
virtue  consists  in  three  things,  as  the  Philosopher  states  in 
Ethic,  ii.  The  first  is  that  man  should  act  knowingly  :  and 
this  is  subject  to  the  judgment  of  both  Divine  and  human 
law;  because  what  a  man  does  in  ignorance,  he  does  acci- 
dentally. Hence  according  to  both  human  and  Divine  law, 
certain  things  are  judged  in  respect  of  ignorance  to  be 
punishable  or  pardonable. 

The  second  point  is  that  a  man  should  act  deliberately, 
i.e.,  from  choice,  choosing  that  particular  action  for  its  own 
sake  ;  wherein  a  twofold  internal  movement  is  implied,  of 
volition  and  of  intention,  about  which  we  have  spoken 
above  (QQ.  VHL,  XU.):  and  concerning  these  two.  Divine 
law  alone,  and  not  human  law,  is  competent  to  judge.  For 
human  law  does  not  punish  the  man  who  wishes  to  slay,  but 
slays  not:  whereas  the  Divine  law  does,  according  to  Matth. 
V.  22:  Whosoever  is  angry  with  his  brother,  shall  be  in  danger 
of  the  judgment. 

The  third  point  is  that  he  should  act  from  a  firm  and  im- 
movable principle  :  which  firmness  belongs  properly  to  a 
habit,  and  implies  that  the  action  proceeds  from  a  rooted 
habit.  In  this  respect,  the  mode  of  virtue  does  not  fall 
under  the  precept  either  of  Divine  or  of  human  law,  since 
neither  by  man  nor  by  God  is  he  punished  as  breaking  the 
law,  who  gives  due  honour  to  his  parents  and  yet  has  not 
the  habit  of  filial  piety. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  mode  of  doing  acts  of  justice,  which 
falls  under  the  precept,  is  that  they  be  done  in  accordance 


139     MORAL  PRl^XEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW      o.  loo.  Airr.  .j 

with  right;  but  not  that  they  be  done  from  the  habit  of 
justice. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  intention  of  the  lawgiver  is  twofold. 
His  aim,  in  the  hrst  place,  is  to  lead  men  to  something  by 
the  precepts  of  the  law:  and  this  is  virtue.  Secondly,  his 
intention  is  brought  to  bear  on  the  matter  itself  of  the  pre- 
cept: and  this  is  something  leading  or  disposing  to  virtue, 
viz.,  an  act  of  virtue.  For  the  end  of  the  precept  and  the 
matter  of  the  precept  are  not  the  same:  just  as  neither  in 
other  things  is  the  end  the  same  as  that  which  conduces  to 
the  end. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  That  works  of  virtue  should  be  done  with- 
out sadness,  falls  under  the  precept  of  the  Divine  law;  for 
whoever  works  with  sadness  works  unwillingly.  But  to 
work  with  pleasure,  i.e.,  joyfully  or  cheerfully,  in  one 
respect  falls  under  the  precept,  viz.,  in  so  far  as  pleasure 
ensues  from  the  love  of  God  and  one's  neighbour  (which 
love  falls  under  the  precept),  and  love  causes  pleasure:  and 
in  another  respect  does  not  fall  under  the  precept,  in  so  far 
as  pleasure  ensues  from  a  habit ;  for  pleasure  taken  in  a  work 
proves  the  existence  of  a  habit,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  ii.  For  an 
act  may  give  pleasure  either  on  account  of  its  end,  or  through 
its  proceeding  from  a  becoming  habit. 

Tenth  Article. 

whether  the  mode  of  charity  falls  under  the  precept 

of  the  divine  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Tenth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  mode  of  charity  falls  under 
the  precept  of  the  Divine  law.  For  it  is  written  (Matth. 
xix.  17) :  //  thou  wilt  enter  into  life,  keep  the  commandments  : 
whence  it  seems  to  follow  that  the  observance  of  the  com- 
mandments suffices  for  entrance  into  life.  But  good  works 
do  not  suffice  for  entrance  into  life,  except  they  be  done 
from  charity:  for  it  is  written  (i  Cor.  xiii.  3):  //  /  should 
distribute  all  my  goods  to  feed  the  poor,  and  if  I  should  deliver 
my  body  to  be  burned,  and  have  not  charity,  it  profUcth  me 


Q.  loo.  Art.  io      THE  '' SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  140 

nothing.  Therefore  the  mode  of  charity  is  included  in  the 
commandment. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  mode  of  charity  consists  properly 
speaking  in  doing  all  things  for  God.  But  this  falls  under 
the  precept;  for  the  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  x.  31):  Do  all  to 
the  glory  of  God.  Therefore  the  mode  of  charity  falls  under 
the  precept. 

Ohj,  3.  Further,  if  the  mode  of  charity  does  not  fall  under 
the  precept,  it  follows  that  one  can  fulfil  the  precepts  of  the 
law  without  having  charity.  Now  what  can  be  done  with- 
out charity  can  be  done  without  grace,  which  is  always 
united  with  charity.  Therefore  one  can  fulfil  the  precepts 
of  the  law  without  grace.  But  this  is  the  error  of  Pelagius, 
as  Augustine  declares  [De  Hceres.  Ixxxviii.).  Therefore  the 
mode  of  charity  is  included  in  the  commandment. 

On  the  contrary,  Whoever  breaks  a  commandment  sins 
mortally.  If  therefore  the  mode  of  charity  falls  under  the 
precept,  it  follows  that  whoever  acts  otherwise  than  from 
charity  sins  mortally.  But  whoever  has  not  charity,  acts 
otherwise  than  from  charity.  Therefore  it  follows  that 
whoever  has  not  charity,  sins  mortally  in  whatever  he  does, 
however  good  this  may  be  in  itself :  which  is  absurd. 

/  answer  that,  Opinions  have  been  contrary  on  this  ques- 
tion. For  some  have  said  absolutely  that  the  mode  of 
charity  comes  under  the  precept ;  and  yet  that  it  is  possible 
for  one  not  having  charity  to  fulfil  this  precept:  because 
he  can  dispose  himself  to  receive  charity  from  God.  Nor 
(say  they)  does  it  follow  that  a  man  not  having  charity 
sins  mortally  whenever  he  does  something  good  of  its  kind: 
because  it  is  an  affirmative  precept  that  binds  one  to  act 
from  charity,  and  is  binding  not  for  all  time,  but  only  for 
such  time  as  one  is  in  a  state  of  charity. — On  the  other 
hand,  some  have  said  that  the  mode  of  charity  is  altogether 
outside  the  precept. 

Both  these  opinions  are  true  up  to  a  certain  point.  Be- 
cause the  act  of  charity  can  be  considered  in  two  ways. 
First,  as  an  act  by  itself:  and  thus  it  falls  under  the  precept 
of  the  law   which   specially  prescribes  it,  viz..   Thou  shalt 


141     MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW    Q  loo.  Art.  io 

love  the  Lord  thy  God,  and  Thou  shalt  love  thy  neighbour. 
In  this  sense,  the  first  opinion  is  true.  Because  it  is  not 
impossible  to  observe  this  precept  which  regards  the  act  of 
charity;  since  man  can  dispose  himself  to  possess  charity, 
and  when  he  possesses  it,  he  can  use  it.  Secondly,  the  act 
of  charity  can  be  considered  as  being  the  mode  of  the  acts 
of  the  other  virtues,  i.e.,  inasmuch  as  the  acts  of  the  other 
virtues  are  ordained  to  charity,  which  is  the  end  of  the  com- 
mandment, as  stated  in  i  Tim.  i.  5 :  for  it  has  been  said  above 
(Q.  XIL,  A.  4)  that  the  intention  of  the  end  is  a  formal 
mode  of  the  act  ordained  to  that  end.  In  this  sense  the 
second  opinion  is  true  in  saying  that  the  mode  of  charity 
does  not  fall  under  the  precept,  that  is  to  say  that  this 
commandment,  Honour  thy  father,  does  not  mean  that  a  man 
must  honour  his  father  from  charity,  but  merely  that  he 
must  honour  him.  Wherefore  he  that  honours  his  father, 
yet  has  not  charity,  does  not  break  this  precept:  although 
he  does  break  the  precept  concerning  the  act  of  charity,  for 
which  reason  he  deserves  to  be  punished. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Our  Lord  did  not  say.  If  thou  wilt  enter  into 
life,  keep  one  commandment ;  but  keep  all  the  commandments  : 
among  which  is  included  the  commandment  concerning  the 
love  of  God  and  our  neighbour. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  precept  of  charity  contains  the  injunc- 
tion that  God  should  be  loved  from  our  whole  heart,  which 
means  that  all  things  would  be  referred  to  God.  Conse- 
quently man  cannot  fulfil  the  precept  of  charity,  unless  he 
also  refer  all  things  to  God.  Wherefore  he  that  honours 
his  father  and  mother,  is  bound  to  honour  them  from 
charity,  not  in  virtue  of  the  precept,  Honour  thy  father  and 
mother,  but  in  virtue  of  the  precept.  Thou  shalt  love  the 
Lord  thy  God  with  thy  whole  heart.  And  since  these  are 
two  affirmative  precepts,  not  binding  for  aU  times,  they 
can  be  binding,  each  one  at  a  different  time:  so  that  it 
may  happen  that  a  man  fulfils  the  precept  of  honouring 
his  father  and  mother,  without  at  the  same  time  break- 
ing the  precept  concerning  the  omission  of  the  mode  of 
charity. 


Q.  TOO.  Art.  ti      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "         142 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Man  cannot  fulfil  all  the  precepts  of  the  law, 
unless  he  fulfil  the  precept  of  charity,  which  is  impossible 
without  charity.  Consequently  it  is  not  possible,  as  Pelagius 
maintained,  for  man  to  fulfil  the  law  without  grace. 


Eleventh  Article. 

whether  it  is  right  to  distinguish  other  moral  pre- 
cepts of  the  law  besides  the  decalogue  ? 

Wc  proceed  thus  to  the  Eleventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  it  is  wrong  to  distinguish  other 
moral  precepts  of  the  law  besides  the  decalogue.  Because, 
as  Our  Lord  declared  (Matth.  xxii.  40),  on  these  two  com- 
mandments of  charity  dependeth  the  whole  law  and  the 
prophets.  But  these  two  commandments  are  explained  by 
the  ten  commandments  of  the  decalogue.  Therefore  there 
is  no  need  for  other  moral  precepts. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  moral  precepts  are  distinct  from  the 
judicial  and  ceremonial  precepts,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCIX. 
AA.  3,  4).  But  the  determinations  of  the  general  moral 
precepts  belong  to  the  judicial  and  ceremonial  precepts: 
and  the  general  moral  precepts  are  contained  in  the  deca- 
logue, or  are  even  presupposed  to  the  decalogue,  as  stated 
above  (A.  3).  Therefore  it  was  unsuitable  to  lay  down 
other  moral  precepts  besides  the  decalogue. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  moral  precepts  are  about  the  acts 
of  all  the  virtues,  as  stated  above  (A.  2).  Therefore,  as  the 
Law  contains,  besides  the  decalogue,  moral  precepts  per- 
taining to  religion,  liberality,  mercy,  and  chastity;  so  there 
should  have  been  added  some  precepts  pertaining  to  the 
other  virtues,  for  instance,  fortitude,  sobriety,  and  so  forth. 
And  yet  such  is  not  the  case.  It  is  therefore  unbecoming 
to  distinguish  other  moral  precepts  in  the  Law  besides  those 
of  the  decalogue. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  xviii.  8) :  The  law  oj  the 
Lord  is  unspotted,  converting  souls.  But  man  is  preserved 
from  the  stain  of  sin,  and  his  soul  is  converted  to  God  by 
other  moral  precepts  besides  those  of  the  decalogue.    There- 


143     MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW    Q.  loo.  Art.  ii 

fore  it  was  right  for  the  Law  to  include  other  moral  pre- 
cepts. 

/  answer  that,  As  is  evident  from  what  has  been  stated 
(Q.  XCIX.,  AA.  3,  4).,  the  judicial  and  ceremonial  precepts 
derive  their  force  from  their  institution  alone :  since  before 
they  were  instituted,  it  seemed  of  no  consequence  whether 
things  were  done  in  this  or  that  way.  But  the  moral  pre- 
cepts derive  their  efficacy  from  the  very  dictate  of  natural 
reason,  even  if  they  were  never  included  in  the  Law.  Now 
of  these  there  are  three  grades:  for  some  are  most  certain, 
and  so  evident  as  to  need  no  promulgation;  such  as  the  com- 
mandments of  the  love  of  God  and  our  neighbour,  and  others 
like  these,  as  stated  above  (A.  3),  which  are,  as  it  were,  the 
ends  of  the  commandments ;  wherefore  no  man  can  have  an 
erroneous  judgment  about  them.  Some  precepts  are  more 
detailed,  the  reason  of  which  even  an  uneducated  man  can 
easily  grasp;  and  yet  they  need  to  be  promulgated,  because 
human  judgment,  in  a  few  instances,  happens  to  be  led 
astray  concerning  them :  these  are  the  precepts  of  the  deca- 
logue. Again,  there  are  some  precepts  the  reason  of  which 
is  not  so  evident  to  everyone,  but  only  to  the  wise;  these 
are  moral  precepts  added  to  the  decalogue,  and  given  to 
the  people  by  God  through  Moses  and  Aaron. 

But  since  the  things  that  are  evident  are  the  principles 
whereby  we  know  those  that  are  not  evident,  these  other 
moral  precepts  added  to  the  decalogue  are  reducible  to 
the  precepts  of  the  decalogue,  as  so  many  corollaries.  Thus 
the  first  commandment  of  the  decalogue  forbids  the  worship 
of  strange  gods:  and  to  this  are  added  other  precepts  for- 
bidding things  relating  to  the  worship  of  idols:  thus  it  is 
written  (Deut.  xviii.  10, 11) :  Neither  let  there  be  found  among 
you  anyone  that  shall  expiate  his  son  or  daughter,  making  them 
to  pass  through  the  fire  :  .  .  .  neither  let  there  he  any  wizard 
nor  charmer,  nor  anyone  thai  consulteih  pythonic  spirits,  or 
fortune-tellers,  or  that  seeketh  the  truth  from  the  dead. — The 
second  commandment  forbids  perjury.  To  this  is  added 
the  prohibition  of  blasphemy  (Levit.  xxiv.  15  seq.)  and  the 
prohibition   of   false   doctrine    (Deut.    xiii.). — To   the   third 


Q.  100.  Art.  ii      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  144 

commandment   are   added   all  the   ceremonial    precepts. — 
To  the  fourth  commandment  prescribing  the  honour  due  to 
parents,  is  added  the  precept  about  honouring  the  aged, 
according  to  Levit.  xix.  32:  Rise  up   before  the  hoary  head, 
and  honour  the  person  of  the  aged  man  ;  and  likewise  all  pre- 
cepts prescribing  the  reverence  to  be  observed  towards  our 
betters,  or  kindliness  towards  our  equals  or  inferiors. — To 
the  fifth  commandment,  which  forbids  murder,  is  added  the 
prohibition  of  hatred  and  of  any  kind  of  violence  inflicted 
on  our  neighbour,  according  to  Levit.  xix.  16:  Thou  shalt 
not  stand  against  the  blood  of  thy  neighbour  :  likewise  the 
prohibition  against  hating  one's  brother   {ibid.   17) :   Thou 
shalt  not  hate  thy  brother  in  thy  heart. — To  the  sixth  command- 
ment   which   forbids    adultery,    is    added    the    prohibition 
about  whoredom,  according  to  Deut.  xxiii.  17:  There  shall 
be  no  whore  among  the  daughters  of  Israel,  nor  whoremonger 
among  the  sons  of  Israel ;  and  the  prohibition  against  un- 
natural sins,  according  to  Levit.  xviii.  22,  23:  Thou  shalt  not 
lie  with  mankind  .  .  .  thou  shalt  not  copulate  with  any  beast. — 
To  the   seventh  commandment  which  prohibits  theft,   is 
added  the   precept  forbidding  usury,   according  to   Deut. 
xxiii.  19 :  Thou  shalt  not  lend  to  thy  brother  money  to  usury  ; 
and  the  prohibition  against  fraud,  according  to  Deut.  xxv. 
13 :  Thou  shalt  not  have  divers  weights  in  thy  bag  ;  and  univer- 
sally all  prohibitions  relating  to  peculations  and  larceny. — 
To  the  eighth  commandment,  forbidding  false  testimony, 
is  added  the  prohibition  against  false  judgment,  according 
to  Exod.  xxiii.  2 :  Neither  shalt  thou  yield  in  judgment,  to  the 
opinion  of  the  most  part,  to  stray  from  the  truth ;  and  the  pro- 
hibition against  lying  {ibid.  7) :  Thou  shalt  fly  lying ;  and  the 
prohibition  against  detraction,  according  to  Levit.  xix.  16: 
Thou  shalt  not  be  a  detractor,  nor  a  whisperer  among  the  people. 
— To  the  other  two  commandments  no  further  precepts  are 
added,  because  thereby  are  forbidden  all  kinds  of  evil  desires. 
Reply  Obj.  i.  The  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  ordained 
to  the  love  of  God  and  our  neighbour  as  pertaining  evidently 
to  our  duty  towards  them;  but  the  other  precepts  are  so 
ordained  as  pertaining  thereto  less  evidently. 


145     MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW     Q.  loo.  Art.  n 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  is  in  virtue  of  their  institution  that  the 
ceremonial  and  judicial  precepts  are  determinations  oj  the 
precepts  of  the  decalogue,  not  by  reason  of  a  natural  instinct, 
as  in  the  case  of  the  superadded  moral  precepts. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  precepts  of  a  law  are  ordained  for  the 
common  good,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2).  And  since 
those  virtues  which  direct  our  conduct  towards  others  per- 
tain directly  to  the  common  good,  as  also  does  the  virtue 
of  chastity,  in  so  far  as  the  generative  act  conduces  to  the 
common  good  of  the  species ;  hence  precepts  bearing  directly 
on  these  virtues  aie  given,  both  in  the  decalogue  and  in 
addition  thereto.  As  to  the  act  of  fortitude  there  are  the 
orders  to  be  given  by  the  commanders  in  the  war,  which  is 
undertaken  for  the  common  good:  as  is  clear  from  Deut. 
XX.  3,  where  the  priest  is  commanded  (to  speak  thus) :  Be 
not  afraid,  do  not  give  back.  In  like  manner  the  prohibition 
of  acts  of  gluttony  is  left  to  paternal  admonition,  since  it 
is  contrary  to  the  good  of  the  household;  hence  it  is  said 
(Deut.  xxi.  20)  in  the  person  of  parents:  He  slighteth  hearing 
our  admonitions,  he  giveth  himself  to  revelling,  and  to  de- 
bauchery and  bapquetings. 

Twelfth  Article. 

whether  the  moral  precepts   of  the   old  law 

justified  man  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Twelfth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  moral  precepts  of  the  Old 
Law  justified  man.  Because  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  ii.  13) : 
For  not  the  hearers  of  the  Law  are  justified  before  God,  but 
the  doers  of  the  Law  shall  be  justified.  But  the  doers  of 
the  Law  are  those  who  fulfil  the  precepts  of  the  Law.  There- 
fore the  fulfilling  of  the  precepts  of  the  Law  was  a  cause  of 
justification. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  it  is  written  (Levit.  xviii.  5) :  Keep  My 
laws  and  My  judgments,  which  if  a  man  do,  he  shall  live  in 
them.  But  the  spiritual  life  of  man  is  through  justice. 
Therefore  the  fulfilling  of  the  precepts  of  the  Law  was  a 
cause  of  justification. 

11. 3  10 


o.  loo.  Art.  12     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  146 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Divine  law  is  more  efficacious  than 
human  law.  But  human  law  justifies  man;  since  there  is 
a  kind  of  justice  consisting  in  fulfilling  the  precepts  of  law. 
Therefore  the  precepts  of  the  Law  justified  man. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (2  Cor.  iii.  6) :  The  letter 
killeth  :  which,  according  to  Augustine  [De  Spir.  et  Lit.  xiv.), 
refers  even  to  the  moral  precepts.  Therefore  the  moral 
precepts  did  not  cause  justice. 

/  answer  that,  Just  as  healthy  is  said  properly  and  first  of 
that  which  is  possessed  of  health,  and  secondarily  of  that 
which  is  a  sign  or  a  safeguard  of  health;  so  justification 
means  first  and  properly  the  causing  of  justice;  while 
secondarily  and  improperly,  as  it  were,  it  may  denote  a 
sign  of  justice  or  a  disposition  thereto.  If  justice  be  taken 
in  the  last  two  ways,  it  is  evident  that  it  was  conferred  by 
the  precepts  of  the  Law;  in  so  far,  to  wit,  as  they  disposed 
men  to  the  justifying  grace  of  Christ,  which  they  also 
signified,  because  as  Augustine  says  [Contra  Faust,  xxii.), 
even  the  life  of  that  people  foretold  and  foreshadowed  Christ, 

But  if  we  speak  of  justification  properly  so  called,  then  we 
must  notice  that  it  can  be  considered  as  in  the  habit  or  as 
in  the  act:  so  that  accordingly  justification  may  be  taken 
in  two  ways.  First,  according  as  man  is  made  just,  by  be- 
coming possessed  of  the  habit  of  justice:  secondly,  according 
as  he  does  works  of  justice,  so  that  in  this  sense  justification 
is  nothing  else  than  the  execution  of  justice.  Now  justice, 
like  the  other  virtues,  may  denote  either  the  acquired  or 
the  infused  virtue,  as  is  clear  from  what  has  been  stated 
(Q.  LXIIL,  A.  4).  The  acquired  virtue  is  caused  by  works; 
but  the  infused  virtue  is  caused  by  God  Himself  through  His 
grace.  The  latter  is  true  justice,  of  which  we  are  speaking 
now,  and  in  respect  of  which  a  man  is  said  to  be  just  before 
God,  according  to  Rom.  iv.  2:  If  Abraham  were  justified  by 
works,  he  hath  whereof  to  glory,  but  not  before  God.  Hence 
this  justice  could  not  be  caused  by  the  moral  precepts, 
which  are  about  human  actions:  wherefore  the  moral  pre- 
cepts could  not  justify  man  by  causing  justice. 

H,  on  the  other  hand,  by  justification  we  understand  the 


147    MORAL  PRECEPTS  OF  OLD  LAW    Q.  ,00.  Art.  12 

execution  of  justice,  thus  all  the  precepts  of  the  Law  justified 
man,  but  in  various  ways.  Because  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts taken  as  a  whole  contained  something  just  in  itself,  in 
so  far  as  they  aimed  at  offering  worship  to  God;  whereas 
taken  individually  they  contained  that  which  is  just,  not  in 
itself,  but  by  being  a  determination  of  the  Divine  law. 
Hence  it  is  said  of  these  precepts  that  they  did  not  justify 
man  save  through  the  devotion  and  obedience  of  those  who 
complied  with  them. — On  the  other  hand  the  moral  and 
judicial  precepts,  either  in  general  or  also  in  particular, 
contained  that  which  is  just  in  itself:  but  the  moral  precepts 
contained  that  which  is  just  in  itself  according  to  that 
general  justice  which  is  every  virtue  according  to  Ethic,  v. : 
whereas  the  judicial  precepts  belonged  to  special  justice, 
which  is  about  contracts  connected  with  the  human  mode 
of  life,  between  one  man  and  another. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  Apostle  takes  justification  for  the  exe- 
cution of  justice. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  man  who  fulfilled  the  precepts  of  the  Law 
is  said  to  live  in  them,  because  he  did  not  incur  the  penalty 
of  death,  which  the  Law  inflicted  on  its  transgressors:  in 
this  sense  the  Apostle  quotes  this  passage  (Gal.  iii.  12). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  precepts  of  human  law  justify  man  by 
acquired  justice:  it  is  not  about  this  that  we  are  inquiring 
now,  but  only  about  that  justice  which  is  before  God. 


QUESTION  CI. 

OF  THE  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS  IN  THEMSELVES. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  ceremonial  precepts:  and  lirst 
we  must  consider  them  in  themselves;  secondly,  their  cause; 
thirdly,  their  duration.  Under  the  first  head  there  are 
four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  The  nature  of  the  ceremonial 
precepts:  (2)  Whether  they  are  figurative  ?  (3)  Whether 
there  should  have  been  many  of  them  ?  (4)  Of  their  various 
kinds. 

First  Article. 

whether  the  nature  of  the  ceremonial  precepts  con- 
sists in  their  pertaining  to  the  worship  of  god  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  nature  of  the  ceremonial 
precepts  does  not  consist  in  their  pertaining  to  the  worship 
of  God.  Because,  in  the  Old  Law,  the  Jews  were  given 
certain  precepts  about  abstinence  from  food  (Levit.  xi.) ; 
and  about  refraining  from  certain  kinds  of  clothes,  e.g. 
(Levit.  xix.  19) :  Thou  shalt  not  wear  a  garment  that  is  woven 
of  two  sorts  ;  and  again  (Num.  xv.  38) :  To  make  to  themselves 
fringes  in  the  corners  of  their  garments.  But  these  are  not 
moral  precepts;  since  they  do  not  remain  in  the  New  Law. 
Nor  are  they  judicial  precepts;  since  they  do  not  pertain 
to  the  pronouncing  of  judgment  between  man  and  man. 
Therefore  they  are  ceremonial  precepts.  Yet  they  seem  in 
no  way  to  pertain  to  the  worship  of  God.  Therefore  the 
nature  of  the  ceremonial  precepts  does  not  consist  m  their 
pertaining  to  Divine  Worship. 

148 


140  THE  CRREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  lor.  Art.  i 

Obj.  2.  Further,  some  state  that  the  ceremonial  precepts 
are  those  which  pertain  to  solemnities;  as  though  they  were 
so  called  from  the  ccfci  (candles)  which  are  lit  up  on  those 
occasions.  But  many  other  things  besides  solemnities 
]Xirtain  to  the  worship  of  God.  Therefore  it  does  not  seem 
that  the  ceremonial  precepts  are  so  called  from  their  per- 
taining to  the  Divine  worship. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  some  say  that  the  ceremonial  precepts 
are  patterns,  i.e.,  rules,  of  salvation:  because  the  Greek 
;)^at/?e  is  the  same  as  the  Latin  salve.  But  all  the  precepts  of 
the  Law  are  rules  of  salvation,  and  not  only  those  that  pertain 
to  the  worship  of  God.  Therefore  not  only  those  precepts 
which  pertain  to  the  Divine  worship  are  called  ceremonial. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Rabbi  Moses  says  (Doctr.  Perplex,  iii.) 
that  the  ceremonial  precepts  are  those  for  which  there  is 
no  evident  reason.  But  there  is  evident  reason  for  many 
things  pertaining  to  the  worship  of  God;  such  as  the  observ- 
ance of  the  Sabbath,  the  feasts  of  the  Passover  and  of  the 
Tabernacles,  and  many  other  things,  the  reason  for  which 
is  set  down  in  the  Law.  Therefore  the  ceremonial  precepts 
are  not  those  which  pertain  to  the  worship  of  God. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Exod.  xviii.  19,  20) :  Be  thou 
to  the  people  in  those  things  that  pertain  to  God  .  .  .  and  .  .  .  shew 
the  people  the  ceremonies  and  the  manner  of  worshipping. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XCIX.,  A.  4),  the  cere- 
monial precepts  are  determinations  of  the  moral  precepts 
whereby  man  is  directed  to  God,  just  as  the  judicial  pre- 
cepts are  determinations  of  the  moral  precepts  whereby  he 
is  directed  to  his  neighbour.  Now  man  is  directed  to  God 
by  the  worship  due  to  Him.  Wherefore  those  precepts 
are  properly  called  ceremonial,  which  pertain  to  the  Divine 
worship. — The  reason  for  their  being  so  called  was  given 
above  {ibid.,  A.  3),  when  we  established  the  distinction 
betv.^een  the  ceremonial  and  the  other  precepts. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  Divine  worship  includes  not  only 
sacrifices  and  the  like,  which  seem  to  be  directed  to  God 
immediately,  but  also  those  things  whereby  His  worshippers 
are  duly  prepared  to  worship  Him :  thus  too  in  other  matters, 


Q.  loT.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  150 

whatever  is  preparatory  to  the  end  comes  under  the  science 
whose  object  is  the  end.  Accordingly  those  precepts  of 
the  Law  which  regard  the  clothing  and  food  of  God's  wor- 
shippers, and  other  such  matters,  pertain  to  a  certain 
preparation  of  the  ministers,  with  the  view  of  fitting  them 
for  the  Divine  worship:  just  as  those  who  administer  to  a 
king  make  use  of  certain  special  observances.  Consequently 
such  are  contained  under  the  ceremonial  precepts. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  alleged  explanation  of  the  name  does 
not  seem  very  probable:  especially  as  the  Law  does  not 
contain  many  instances  of  the  lighting  of  candles  in  solem- 
nities; since,  even  the  lamps  of  the  Candlestick  were  fur- 
nished with  oil  of  olives,  as  stated  in  Levit.  xxiv.  2.  Never- 
theless we  may  say  that  all  things  pertaining  to  the  Divine 
worship  were  more  carefully  observed  on  solemn  festivals: 
so  that  all  ceremonial  precepts  may  be  included  under  the 
observance  of  solemnities. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Neither  does  this  explanation  of  the  name 
appear  to  be  very  much  to  the  point,  since  the  word  ceremony 
is  not  Greek  but  Latin.  We  may  say,  however,  that,  since 
man's  salvation  is  from  God,  those  precepts  above  all  seem 
to  be  rules  of  salvation,  which  direct  man  to  God:  and  ac- 
cordingly those  which  refer  to  Divine  worship  are  called 
ceremonial  precepts. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  This  explanation  of  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts has  a  certain  amount  of  probability:  not  that  they  are 
called  ceremonial  precisely  because  there  is  no  evident 
reason  for  them;  this  is  a  kind  of  consequence.  For,  since 
the  precepts  referring  to  the  Divine  worship  must  needs  be 
figurative,  as  we  shall  state  further  on  (A.  2),  the  consequence 
is  that  the  reason  for  them  is  not  so  very  evident. 

Second  Article, 
whether  the  ceremonial  precepts  are  figurative  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 
Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  the  ceremonial  precepts  are  not 
figurative.     For  it  is  the  duty  of  every  teacher  to  express 


151  THE  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  tot.  Art.  2 

himself  in  such  a  way  as  to  be  easily  understood,  as  Augus- 
tine states  (De  Doctr.  Christ,  iv.) :  and  this  seems  very 
necessary  in  the  framing  of  a  law:  because  precepts  of  law 
are  proposed  to  the  populace ;  for  which  reason  a  law  should 
be  manifest,  as  Isidore  declares  [Etym.  ii.).  If  therefore 
the  precepts  of  the  Law  were  given  as  figures  of  something, 
it  seems  unbecoming  that  Moses  should  have  delivered  these 
precepts  without  explaining  what  they  signified. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  whatever  is  done  for  the  worship  of  God, 
should  be  entirely  free  from  unfittingness.  But  the  per- 
formance of  actions  in  representation  of  others,  seems  to 
savour  of  the  theatre  or  of  the  drama:  because  formerly 
the  actions  performed  in  theatres  were  done  to  represent 
the  actions  of  others.  Therefore  it  seems  that  such  things 
should  not  be  done  for  the  worship  of  God.  But  the  cere- 
monial precepts  are  ordained  to  the  Divine  worship,  as  stated 
above  (A.  i).     Therefore  they  should  not  be  figurative. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  {Enchirid.  iii.,  iv.)  that 
God  is  worshipped  chiefly  by  faith,  hope,  and  charity.  But 
the  precepts  of  faith,  hope,  and  charity  are  not  figurative. 
Therefore  the  ceremonial  precepts  should  not  be  figurative. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Our  Lord  said  (John  iv.  24) :  God  is  a 
spirit,  and  they  that  adore  Him,  must  adore  Him  in  spirit  and 
in  truth.  But  a  figure  is  not  the  very  truth:  in  fact  one  is 
condivided  with  the  other.  Therefore  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts, which  refer  to  the  Divine  worship,  should  not  be 
figurative. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Coloss.  ii.  16,  17) :  Let 
no  man  .  .  .  judge  you  in  meat  or  in  drink,  or  in  respect  of  a 
festival  day,  or  of  the  new  moon,  or  of  the  sabbaths,  which  arc 
a  shadow  of  things  to  come. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  i ;  Q.  XCIX.,  AA.  3,  4), 
the  ceremonial  precepts  are  those  which  refer  to  the  worship 
of  God.  Now  the  Divine  worship  is  twofold:  internal,  and 
external.  For  since  man  is  composed  of  soul  and  body, 
each  of  these  should  be  applied  to  the  worship  of  God;  the 
soul  by  an  interior  worship ;  the  body  by  an  outward  wor- 
ship: hence  it  is  written  (Ps.  Ixxxiii.  3):  My  heart  and  my 


Q.  TOT.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  152 

flesh  have  rejoiced  in  the  living  God.  And  as  the  body  is 
ordained  to  God  through  the  soul,  so  the  outward  worship 
is  ordained  to  the  internal  worship.  Now  interior  worship 
consists  in  the  soul  being  united  to  God  by  the  intellect 
and  affections.  Wherefore  according  to  the  various  ways 
in  which  the  intellect  and  affections  of  the  man  who  worships 
God  are  rightly  united  to  God,  his  external  actions  are 
applied  in  various  ways  to  the  Divine  worship. 

For  in  the  state  of  future  bliss,  the  human  intellect  will 
gaze  on  the  Divine  Truth  in  Itself.  Wherefore  the  external 
worship  will  not  consist  in  anything  figurative,  but  solely 
in  the  praise  of  God,  proceeding  from  the  inward  knowledge 
and  affection,  according  to  Isa.  li.  3:  Joy  and  gladness  shall 
he  found  therein,  thanksgiving  and  the  voice  of  'praise. 

But  in  the  present  state  of  life,  we  are  unable  to  gaze 
upon  the  Divine  Truth  in  Itself,  and  we  need  the  ray  of 
Divine  light  to  shine  upon  us  under  the  form  of  certain 
sensible  figures,  as  Dionysius  states  [Ccel.  Hier.  i.) ;  in  various 
ways,  however,  according  to  the  various  states  of  human 
knowledge.  For  under  the  Old  Law,  neither  was  the  Divine 
Truth  manifest  in  Itself,  nor  was  the  way  leading  to  that 
manifestation  as  yet  opened  out,  as  the  Apostle  declares 
(Heb.  ix.  8).  Hence  the  external  worship  of  the  Old  Law 
needed  to  be  figurative  not  only  of  the  future  truth  to  be 
manifested  in  our  heavenly  country,  but  also  of  Christ, 
Who  is  the  way  leading  to  that  heavenly  manifestation. 
But  under  the  New  Law  this  way  is  already  revealed:  and 
therefore  it  needs  no  longer  to  be  foreshadowed  as  something 
future,  but  to  be  brought  to  our  minds  as  something  past  or 
present:  and  the  truth  of  the  glory  to  come,  which  is  not 
yet  revealed,  alone  needs  to  be  foreshadowed.  This  is 
what  the  Apostle  says  (Heb.  x.  i) :  The  Law  has  (Vulg., — 
having)  a  shadow  of  the  good  things  to  come,  not  the  very  image 
of  the  things  :  for  a  shadow  is  less  than  an  image ;  so  that 
the  image  belongs  to  the  New  Law,  but  the  shadow  to 
the  Old. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  things  of  God  are  not  to  be  revealed 
to  man  except  in  proportion  to  his  capacity:  else  he 
would  be  in  danger  of  downfall,  were  he  to  despise  what 


153  THE  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  ioi.Art.  3 

he  cannot  grasp.  Hence  it  was  more  beneficial  that  the 
Divine  mysteries  should  be  revealed  to  uncultured  people 
under  a  veil  of  figures,  that  thus  they  might  know  them  at 
least  implicitly  by  using  those  figures  to  the  honour  of  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Just  as  human  reason  fails  to  grasp  poetical 
expressions  on  account  of  their  being  lacking  in  truth,  so 
does  it  fail  to  grasp  Divine  things  perfectly,  on  account  of 
the  sublimity  of  the  truth  they  contain:  and  therefore  in 
both  cases  there  is  need  of  signs  by  means  of  sensible  figures. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Augustine  is  speaking  there  of  internal 
worship ;  to  which,  however,  external  worship  should  be 
ordained,  as  stated  above. 

The  same  answer  applies  to  the  Fourth  Objection :  because 
men  were  taught  by  Him  to  practise  more  perfectly  the 
spiritual  worship  of  God. 

Third  Article. 

whether  there  should  have  been  many  ceremonial 

precepts  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  should  not  have  been 
many  ceremonial  precepts.  For  those  things  which  con- 
duce to  an  end  should  be  proportionate  to  that  end.  But 
the  ceremonial  precepts,  as  stated  above  (A A.  i,  2),  are 
ordained  to  the  worship  of  God,  and  to  the  foreshadowing 
of  Christ.  Now  there  is  but  one  God,  of  Whom  are  all  things, 
.  .  .  and  one  Lord  Jesus  Christ,  by  Whom  are  all  things  (i  Cor. 
viii.  6).  Therefore  there  should  not  have  been  many  cere- 
monial precepts. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  great  number  of  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts was  an  occasion  of  transgression,  according  to  the 
words  of  Peter  (Acts  xv.  10)  :  Why  tempt  you  God,  to  put  a 
yoke  upon  the  necks  of  the  disciples,  which  neither  our  fathers 
nor  we  have  been  able  to  bear  ?  Now  the  transgression  of 
the  Divine  precepts  is  an  obstacle  to  man's  salvation.  Since, 
therefore,  every  law  should  conduce  to  man's  salvation,  as 
Isidore  says  (Etym.  ii.),  it  seems  that  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts should  not  have  been  given  in  great  number. 


Q.  loi.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  154 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  ceremonial  precepts  referred  to  the 
outward  and  bodily  worship  of  God,  as  stated  above  (A.  2) . 
But  the  Law  should  have  lessened  this  bodily  worship: 
since  it  directed  men  to  Christ,  Who  taught  them  to  worship 
God  in  spirit  and  in  truth,  as  stated  in  John  iv.  23.  There- 
fore there  should  not  have  been  many  ceremonial  precepts. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Osee  viii.  12) :  7  shall  write 
to  them  (Vulg., — him)  My  manifold  laws  ;  and  (Job  xi.  6): 
That  He  might  show  thee  the  secrets  of  His  wisdom,  and  that 
His  Law  is  manifold. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XCVL,  A.  i),  every 
law  is  given  to  a  people.  Now  a  people  contains  two  kinds 
of  men:  some,  prone  to  evil,  who  have  to  be  coerced  by  the 
precepts  of  the  law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCV.,  A.  i) ;  some, 
inclined  to  good,  either  from  nature  or  from  custom,  or 
rather  from  grace;  and  the  like  have  to  be  taught  and  im- 
proved by  means  of  the  precepts  of  the  law.  Accordingly, 
with  regard  to  both  kinds  of  men  it  was  expedient  that  the 
Old  Law  should  contain  many  ceremonial  precepts.  For 
in  that  people  there  were  many  prone  to  idolatry ;  wherefore 
it  was  necessary  to  recall  them  by  means  of  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts from  the  worship  of  idols  to  the  worship  of  God. 
And  since  men  served  idols  in  many  ways,  it  was  necessary 
on  the  other  hand  to  devise  many  means  of  repressing  every 
single  one :  and  again,  to  lay  many  obligations  on  suchlike 
men,  in  order  that  being  burdened,  as  it  were,  by  their 
duties  to  the  Divine  worship,  they  might  have  no  time  for 
the  service  of  idols.  As  to  those  who  were  inclined  to  good, 
it  was  again  necessary  that  there  should  be  many  ceremonial 
precepts;  both  because  thus  their  mind  was  turned  to  God 
in  many  ways,  and  more  continually;  and  because  the 
mystery  of  Christ,  which  was  foreshadowed  by  these  cere- 
monial precepts,  brought  many  boons  to  the  world,  and 
afforded  men  many  considerations,  which  needed  to  be 
signified  by  various  ceremonies. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  When  that  which  conduces  to  an  end  is 
sufficient  to  conduce  thereto,  then  one  such  thing  suffices 
for  one  end:  thus  one  remedy,  if  it  be  efficacious,  suffices 


155  THE  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     O.  tot.  Art.  3 

sometimes  to  restore  man  to  health,  and  then  the  remedy 
needs  not  to  be  repeated.  But  when  that  which  conduces 
to  an  end  is  weak  and  imperfect,  it  needs  to  be  multiphed: 
thus  many  remedies  are  given  to  a  sick  man,  when  one  is 
not  enough  to  heal  him.  Now  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old 
Law  were  weak  and  imperfect,  both  for  representing  the 
mystery  of  Christ,  on  account  of  its  surpassing  excellence; 
and  for  subjugating  men's  minds  to  God.  Hence  the  Apostle 
says  (Heb.  vii.  18.,  19):  There  is  a  setting  aside  of  the  former 
commandment  because  of  the  weakness  and  unprofitableness 
thereof,  for  the  law  brought  nothing  to  perfection.  Conse- 
quently these  ceremonies  needed  to  be  in  great  number. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  A  wise  lawgiver  should  suffer  lesser  trans- 
gressions, that  the  greater  may  be  avoided.  And  therefore, 
in  order  to  avoid  the  sin  of  idolatry,  and  the  pride  which 
would  arise  in  the  hearts  of  the  Jews,  were  they  to  fulfil  all 
the  precepts  of  the  Law,  the  fact  that  they  would  in  con- 
sequence find  many  occasions  of  disobedience  did  not  pre- 
vent God  from  giving  them  many  ceremonial  precepts. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  Old  Law  lessened  bodily  worship  in 
many  ways.  Thus  it  forbade  sacrifices  to  be  offered  in 
every  place  and  by  any  person.  Many  suchlike  things  did 
it  enact  for  the  lessening  of  bodily  worship ;  as  Rabbi  Moses 
the  Egyptian  testifies  (Doct.  Perplex,  iii.).  Nevertheless  it 
behoved  not  to  attenuate  the  bodily  worship  of  God  so  much 
as  to  allow  men  to  fall  away  into  the  worship  of  idols. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  ceremonies  of  the  old  law  are  suitably 
divided  into  sacrifices,  sacred  things,  sacraments, 
and  observances  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law 
are  unsuitably  divided  into  sacrifices,  sacred  things,  sacra- 
ments and  observances.  For  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old 
Law  foreshadowed  Christ.  But  this  was  done  only  by  the 
sacrifices,  which  foreshadowed  the  sacrifice  in  which  Christ 


Q.  Toi.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  156 

delivered  Himself  an  oblation  and  a  sacrifice  to  God  (Eph.  v.  2). 
Therefore  none  but  the  sacrifices  were  ceremonies. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  Old  Law  was  ordained  to  the  New. 
But  in  the  New  Law  the  sacrifice  is  the  Sacrament  of  the 
Altar.  Therefore  in  the  Old  Law  there  should  be  no  dis- 
tinction between  sacrifices  and  sacraments. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  a  sacred  thing  is  something  dedicated  to 
God:  in  which  sense  the  tabernacle  and  its  vessels  were 
said  to  be  consecrated.  But  all  the  ceremonial  precepts 
were  ordained  to  the  worship  of  God,  as  stated  above  (A.  i). 
Therefore  all  ceremonies  were  sacred  things.  Therefore  sacred 
things  should  not  be  taken  as  a  part  of  the  ceremonies. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  Observances  are  so  called  from  having 
to  be  observed.  But  all  the  precepts  of  the  Law  had  to  be 
observed:  for  it  is  written  (Deut.  viii.  11) :  Observe  (Douay, — 
Take  heed)  and  beware  lest  at  any  time  thou  forget  the  Lord 
thy  God,  and  neglect  His  commandments  and  judgments  and 
ceremonies.  Therefore  the  observances  should  not  be  con- 
sidered as  a  part  of  the  ceremonies. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  the  solemn  festivals  are  reckoned  as  part 
of  the  ceremonial:  since  they  were  a  shadow  of  things  to 
come  (Coloss.  ii.  16,  17) :  and  the  same  may  be  said  of  the 
oblations  and  gifts,  as  appears  from  the  words  of  the  Apostle 
(Heb.  ix.  9) :  and  yet  these  do  not  seem  to  be  included 
in  any  of  those  mentioned  above.  Therefore  the  above 
division  of  ceremonies  is  unsuitable. 

On  the  contrary,  In  the  Old  Law  each  of  the  above  is  called 
a  ceremony.  For  the  sacrifices  are  called  ceremonies 
(Num.  XV.  24) :  They  shall  offer  a  calf  .  .  .  and  the  sacrifices 
and  libations  thereof,  as  the  ceremonies  require.  Of  the  sacra- 
ment of  Order  it  is  written  (Levit.  vii.  35) :  This  is  the  anoint- 
ing of  Aaron  and  his  sons  in  the  ceremonies.  Of  sacred  things 
also  it  is  written  (Exod.  xxxviii.  21) :  These  are  the  instru- 
ments of  the  tabernacle  of  the  testimony  .  .  .  in  the  ceremonies 
of  the  Levites.  And  again  of  the  observances  it  is  written 
(3  Kings  ix.  6) :  If  you  .  .  .  shall  turn  away  from  following  Me, 
and  will  not  observe  (Doua.y, — keep)  My  .  .  .  ceremonies  which 
I  have  set  before  you. 


157  THE  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  loi.  Art.  4 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A A.  i,  2),  the  ceremonial 
precepts  are  ordained  to  the  Divine  worship.  Now  in  this 
worship  we  may  consider  the  worship  itself,  the  worshippers, 
and  the  instruments  of  worship.  The  worship  consists 
specially  in  sacrifices,  which  are  offered  up  in  honour  of  God. 
— The  instruments  of  worship  refer  to  the  sacred  things, 
such  as  the  tabernacle,  the  vessels  and  so  forth. — With  re- 
gard to  the  worshippers  two  points  may  be  considered.  The 
first  point  is  their  preparation  for  Divine  worship,  which  is 
effected  by  a  sort  of  consecration  either  of  the  people  or  of 
the  ministers;  and  to  this  the  sacraments  refer.  The  second 
point  is  their  particular  mode  of  life,  whereby  they  are 
distinguished  from  those  who  do  not  worship  God:  and  to 
this  pertain  the  observances,  for  instance,  in  matters  of  food, 
clothing,  and  so  forth. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  It  was  necessary  for  the  sacrifices  to  be 
offered  both  in  some  certain  place  and  by  some  certain 
men:  and  all  this  pertained  to  the  worship  of  God.  Where- 
fore just  as  their  sacrifices  signified  Christ  the  victim,  so 
too  their  sacraments  and  sacred  things  foreshadowed  the 
sacraments  and  sacred  things  of  the  New  Law;  while  their 
observances  foreshadowed  the  mode  of  life  of  the  people 
under  the  New  Law:  all  of  which  things  pertain  to  Christ. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  sacrifice  of  the  New  Law,  viz.,  the 
Eucharist,  contains  Christ  Himself,  the  Author  of  our  Sancti- 
fication :  for  He  sanctified  the  people  by  His  own  blood  (Heb. 
xiii.  12).  Hence  this  Sacrifice  is  also  a  sacrament.  But  the 
sacrifices  of  the  Old  Law  did  not  contain  Christ,  but  fore- 
shadowed Him;  hence  they  are  not  called  sacraments.  In 
order  to  signify  this  there  were  certain  sacraments  apart 
from  the  sacrifices  of  the  Old  Law,  which  sacraments  were 
figures  of  the  sanctification  to  come.  Nevertheless  to 
certain  consecrations  certain  sacrifices  were  united. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  sacrifices  and  sacraments  were  of 
course  sacred  things.  But  certain  things  were  sacred, 
through  being  dedicated  to  the  Divine  worship,  and  yet  were 
not  sacrifices  or  sacraments:  wherefore  they  retained  the 
common  designation  of  sacred  things. 


Q.  101.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUJVIMA  THEOLOGICA  "  158 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Those  things  which  pertained  to  the  mode  of 
Hfe  of  the  people  who  worshipped  God,  retained  the  common 
designation  of  observances,  in  so  far  as  they  fell  short  of 
the  above.  For  they  were  not  called  sacred  things,  because 
they  had  no  immediate  connection  with  the  worship  of  God, 
such  as  the  tabernacle  and  its  vessels  had.  But  by  a  sort 
of  consequence  they  were  matters  of  ceremony,  in  so  far  as 
they  affected  the  fitness  of  the  people  who  worshipped  God. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  Just  as  the  sacrifices  were  offered  in  a  fixed 
place,  so  were  they  offered  at  fixed  times:  for  which  reason 
the  solemn  festivals  seem  to  be  reckoned  among  the  sacred 
things.-— The  oblations  and  gifts  are  counted  together  with 
the  sacrifices ;  hence  the  Apostle  says  (Heb.  v.  i) :  Every 
high-priest  taken  from  among  men,  is  ordained  for  men  in 
things  that  appertain  to  God,  that  he  may  offer  up  gifts  and 
sacrifices. 


QUESTION  CIl. 

OL-    J  HE  CAUSES  OF  THE  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS. 

{In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  causes  of  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts: under  which  head  there  are  six  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  there  was  any  cause  for  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts ?  (2)  Whether  the  cause  of  the  ceremonial  precepts 
was  literal  or  hgurative  ?  (3)  The  causes  of  the  sacrifices. 
(4)  The  causes  of  the  sacraments.  (5)  The  causes  of  the 
sacred  things.     (6)  The  causes  of  the  observances. 

First  Article. 

whether  there  was  any  cause  for  the  ceremonial 

precepts  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  was  no  cause  for  the 
ceremonial  precepts.  Because  on  Ephes.  ii.  15,  Making 
void  the  law  of  the  commandments,  the  gloss  says,  i.e.,  making 
void  the  Old  Law  as  to  the  carnal  observances,  by  substituting 
decrees,  i.e.,  evangelical  precepts,  which  are  based  on  reason. 
But  if  the  observances  of  the  Old  Law  were  based  on  reason, 
it  would  have  been  useless  to  void  them  by  the  reasonable 
decrees  of  the  New  Law.  Therefore  there  was  no  reason 
for  the  ceremonial  observances  of  the  Old  Law. 

Ob]'.  2.  Further,  the  Old  Law  succeeded  the  law  of  nature. 
But  in  the  law  of  nature  there  was  a  precept  for  which  there 
was  no  reason  save  that  man's  obedience  might  be  tested; 
as  Augustine  says  {Gen.  ad  lit.  viii.),  concerning  the  pro- 
hibition about  the  tree  of  life.     Therefore  in  the  Old  Law 

159 


Q.  102.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  i6o 

there  should  have  been  some  precepts  for  the  purpose  of 
testing  man's  obedience,  having  no  reason  in  themselves. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  man's  works  are  called  moral  according 
as  they  proceed  from  reason.  If  therefore  there  is  any 
reason  for  the  ceremonial  precepts,  they  would  not  differ 
from  the  moral  precepts.  It  seems  therefore  that  there 
was  no  cause  for  the  ceremonial  precepts:  for  the  reason  of 
a  precept  is  taken  from  some  cause. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  xviii.  9) :  The  command- 
ment of  the  Lord  is  lightsome,  enlightening  the  eyes.  But 
the  ceremonial  precepts  are  commandments  of  God.  There- 
fore they  are  lightsome:  and  yet  they  would  not  be  so,  if 
they  had  no  reasonable  cause.  Therefore  the  ceremonial 
precepts  have  a  reasonable  cause. 

I  answer  that,  Since,  according  to  the  Philosopher 
(Metaph.  i.),  it  is  the  function  of  a  wise  man  to  do  everything 
in  order,  those  things  which  proceed  from  the  Divine  wisdom 
must  needs  be  well  ordered,  as  the  Apostle  states  (Rom. 
xiii.  i).  Now  there  are  two  conditions  required  for  things 
to  be  well  ordered.  First,  that  they  be  ordained  to  their 
due  end,  which  is  the  principle  of  the  whole  order  in  matters 
of  action:  since  those  things  that  happen  by  chance  outside 
the  intention  of  the  end,  or  which  are  not  done  seriously 
but  for  fun,  are  said  to  be  inordinate.  Secondly,  that  which 
is  done  in  view  of  the  end  should  be  proportionate  to  the 
end.  From  this  it  follows  that  the  reason  for  whatever 
conduces  to  the  end  is  taken  from  the  end:  thus  the  reason 
for  the  disposition  of  a  saw  is  taken  from  cutting,  which  is 
its  end,  as  stated  in  Phys.  ii.  Now  it  is  evident  that  the 
ceremonial  precepts,  like  all  the  other  precepts  of  the  Law, 
were  institutions  of  Divine  wisdom:  hence  it  is  \vritten 
(Deut.  iv.  6) :  This  is  your  wisdom  and  understanding  in  the 
sight  of  nations.  Consequently  we  must  needs  say  that 
the  ceremonial  precepts  were  ordained  to  a  certain  end, 
wherefrom  their  reasonable  causes  can  be  gathered. 

Reply  Ob],  i.  It  may  be  said  that  there  was  no  reason  for 
the  observances  of  the  Old  Law,  in  the  sense  that  there  was 
no  reason  in  the  very  nature  of  the  thing  done :  for  instance 


i6i  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  2 

that  a  garment  should  not  be  made  of  wool  and  linen. 
But  there  could  be  a  reason  for  them  in  their  relation  to 
something  else :  namely,  in  so  far  as  something  was  signified 
or  excluded  thereby.  On  the  other  hand,  the  decrees  of 
the  New  Law,  which  refer  chiefly  to  faith  and  the  love  of 
God,  are  reasonable  from  the  very  nature  of  the  act. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  reason  for  the  prohibition  concerning 
the  tree  of  the  knowledge  of  good  and  evil  was  not  that  this 
tree  was  naturally  evil:  and  yet  this  prohibition  was  reason- 
able in  its  relation  to  something  else,  in  as  much  as  it  signi- 
fied something.  And  so  also  the  ceremonial  precepts  of 
the  Old  Law  were  reasonable  on  account  of  their  relation 
to  something  else. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  moral  precepts  in  their  very  nature 
have  reasonable  causes:  as  for  instance.  Thou  shall  not 
kill,  Thou  shall  not  steal.  But  the  ceremonial  precepts 
have  a  reasonable  cause  in  their  relation  to  something  else, 
as  stated  above. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  ceremonial  precepts  have    a  literal 
cause  or  merely  a  figurative  cause  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  ceremonial  precepts  have 
not  a  literal,  but  merely  a  figurative,  cause.  For  among 
the  ceremonial  precepts,  the  chief  were  circumcision  and  the 
sacrifice  of  the  paschal  lamb.  But  neither  of  these  had  any 
but  a  figurative  cause:  because  each  was  given  as  a  sign. 
For  it  is  written  (Gen.  xvii.  11) :  You  shall  circumcise  the  flesh 
of  your  foreskin,  that  it  may  be  for  a  sign  of  the  covenant 
between  Me  and  you:  and  of  the  celebration  of  the  Passover  it 
is  written  (Exod.  xiii.  9) :  It  shall  be  as  a  sign  in  thy  hand,  and 
as  a  manorial  before  thy  eyes.  Therefore  much  more  did  the 
other  ceremonial  precepts  have  none  but  a  figurative  reason. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  an  effect  is  proportionate  to  its  cause. 
But  all  the  ceremonial  precepts  are  figurative,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  CL,  A.  2).  Therefore  they  have  no  other  than 
a  figurative  cause. 

n.  3  u 


g.  102.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  162 

Obj.  3.  Further,  if  it  be  a  matter  of  indifference  wliether  a 
certain  tiling,  considered  in  itseff,  be  done  in  a  particular  way 
or  not,  it  seems  that  it  has  not  a  literal  cause.  Now  there  are 
certain  points  in  the  ceremonial  precepts,  which  appear  to  be 
a  matter  of  indifference,  as  to  whether  they  be  done  in  one 
way  or  in  another:  for  instance,  the  number  of  animals  to  be 
offered,  and  other  such  particular  circumstances.  Therefore 
there  is  no  literal  cause  for  the  precepts  of  the  Ofd  Law. 

On  the  contrary,  Just  as  the  ceremonial  precepts  fore- 
shadowed Christ,  so  did  the  stories  of  the  Old  Testament: 
for  it  is  written  (i  Cor.  x.  11)  that  all  {these  things)  happened 
to  them  in  figure.  Now  in  the  stories  of  the  Old  Testament, 
besides  the  mystical  or  figurative,  there  is  the  literal  sense. 
Therefore  the  ceremonial  precepts  had  also  literal,  besides 
their  figurative  causes. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  i) ,  the  reason  for  what- 
ever conduces  to  an  end  must  be  taken  from  that  end. 
Now  the  end  of  the  ceremonial  precepts  was  twofold:  for 
they  were  ordained  to  the  Divine  worship,  for  that  par- 
ticular time,  and  to  the  foreshadowing  of  Christ;  just  as 
the  words  of  the  prophets  regarded  the  time  being  in  such  a 
way  as  to  be  utterances  figurative  of  the  time  to  come,  as 
Jerome  says  on  Osee  i.  3.  Accordingly  the  reasons  for  the 
ceremonial  precepts  of  the  Old  Law  can  be  taken  in  two 
ways.  First,  in  respect  of  the  Divine  worship  which  was  to 
be  observed  for  that  particular  time:  and  these  reasons  are 
literal:  whether  they  refer  to  the  shunning  of  idolatry;  or 
recall  certain  Divine  benefits ;  or  remind  men  of  the  Divine 
excellence;  or  point  out  the  disposition  of  mind  which  was 
then  required  in  those  who  worshipped  God. — Secondly, 
their  reasons  can  be  gathered  from  the  point  of  view  of  their 
being  ordained  to  foreshadow  Christ :  and  thus  their  reasons 
are  figurative  and  mystical:  whether  they  be  taken  from 
Christ  Himself  and  the  Church,  which  pertains  to  the 
allegorical  sense;  or  to  the  morals  of  the  Chiistian  people, 
which  pertains  to  the  moral  sense;  or  to  the  state  of  future 
glory,  in  as  much  as  we  are  brought  thereto  by  Christ, 
which  refers  to  the  anagogical  sense. 


i63  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  3 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Just  as  the  use  oi  inetaphorical  expressions 
in  Scripture  belongs  to  the  hteral  sense,  because  the  words 
are  employed  in  order  to  convey  that  particular  meaning; 
so  also  the  meaning  of  those  legal,  ceremonies  which  com- 
memorated certain  Divine  benehts,  on  account  of  which 
they  were  instituted,  and  of  others  similar  which  belonged 
to  that  time,  does  not  go  beyond  the  order  of  literal  causes. 
Consequently  when  we  assert  that  the  cause  of  the  celebra- 
tion of  the  Passover  was  its  signihcation  of  the  delivery 
from  Egypt,  or  that  circumcision  was  a  sign  of  God's  cove- 
nant with  Abraham,  we  assign  the  literal  cause. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  argument  would  avail,  if  the  ceremonial 
precepts  had  been  given  merely  as  figures  of  things  to  come, 
and  not  for  the  purpose  of  worshipping  God  then  and  there. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  we  stated  when  speaking  of  human  laws 
(Q.  XCVL,  AA.  I,  6),  there  is  a  reason  for  them  in  the 
abstract,  but  not  in  regard  to  particular  conditions,  which 
depend  on  the  judgment  of  those  who  frame  them;  so  also 
many  particular  determinations  in  the  ceremonies  of  the 
Old  Law  have  no  literal  cause,  but  only  a  figurative  cause; 
whereas  in  the  abstract  they  have  a  literal  cause. 

Third  Article. 

whether  a  suitable  cause  can  be  assigned  for  the 
ceremonies  which  pertained  to  sacrifices  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Jliird  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  no  suitable  cause  can  be 
assigned  for  the  ceremonies  pertaining  to  sacrifices.  For 
those  things  which  were  offered  in  sacrifice,  are  those  which 
are  necessary  for  sustaining  human  life:  such  as  certain 
animals  and  certain  loaves.  But  God  needs  no  such  sus- 
tenance ;  according  to  Ps.  xlix.  13 :  Shall  I  eat  the  flesh  of 
bullocks  ?  Or  shall  I  drink  the  blood  of  goats  ?  Therefore 
such  sacrifices  were  unfittingly  offered  to  God. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  only  three  kinds  of  quadrupeds  were 
offered  in  sacrifice  to  God,  viz.,  oxen,  sheep  and  goats;  of 
birds,  generally  the  turtledove  and  the  dove;  but  specially. 


(}.  I02.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  164 

in  the  cleansing  of  a  leper,  an  offering  was  made  of  sparrows. 
Now  many  other  animals  are  more  noble  than  these.  Since 
therefore  whatever  is  best  should  be  offered  to  God,  it  seems 
that  not  only  of  these  three  should  sacrifices  have  been 
offered  to  Him. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  just  as  man  has  received  from  God  the 
dominion  over  birds  and  beasts,  so  also  has  he  received 
dominion  over  fishes.  Consequently  it  was  unfitting  for 
fishes  to  be  excluded  from  the  divine  sacrifices. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  turtledoves  and  doves  indifferently  are 
commanded  to  be  offered  up.  Since  then  the  young  of  the 
dove  are  commanded  to  be  offered,  so  also  should  the  young 
of  the  turtledove. 

Ohj.  5.  Further,  God  is  the  Author  of  life,  not  only  of 
men,  but  also  of  animals,  as  is  clear  from  Gen.  i.  20,  seq. 
Now  death  is  opposed  to  life.  Therefore  it  was  fitting  that 
living  animals  rather  than  slain  animals  should  be  offered 
to  God  ;  especially  as  the  Apostle  admonishes  us  (Rom. 
xii.  i),  to  present  our  bodies  a  living  sacrifice,  holy,  pleasing 
unto  God. 

Ohj.  6.  Further,  if  none  but  slain  animals  were  offered  in 
sacrifice  to  God,  it  seems  that  it  mattered  not  how  they 
were  slain.  Therefore  it  was  unfitting  that  the  manner  of 
immolation  should  be  determined,  especially  as  regards  birds 
(Levit.  i.  15,  seq.). 

Ohj.  7.  Further,  every  defect  in  an  animal  is  a  step 
towards  corruption  and  death.  If  therefore  slain  animals 
were  offered  to  God,  it  was  unreasonable  to  forbid  the 
offering  of  an  imperfect  animal,  e.g.,  a  lame,  or  a  blind,  or 
otherwise  defective  animal. 

Ohj.  8.  Further,  those  who  offer  victims  to  God  should 
partake  thereof,  according  to  the  words  of  the  Apostle 
(i  Cor.  X.  j.^):  Are  not  they  that  eat  of  the  sacrifices  partakers 
of  the  altar  ?  It  was  therefore  unbecoming  for  the  offerers 
to  be  denied  certain  parts  of  the  victims,  namely,  the  blood, 
the  fat,  the  breast-bone  and  the  right  shoulder. 

Ohj.  9.  Further,  just  as  holocausts  were  offered  up  in 
honour  of  God,  so  also  were  the  peace-offerings  and  sin- 


i65  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  3 

offerings.  But  no  female  animal  was  offered  up  to  God  as 
a  holocaust,  although  holocausts  were  offered  of  both 
quadrupeds  and  birds.  Therefore  it  was  inconsistent  that 
female  animals  should  be  offered  up  in  peace-offerings  and 
sin-offerings,  and  that  nevertheless  birds  should  not  be 
offered  up  in  peace-offerings. 

Obj.  10.  Further,  all  the  peace-offerings  seem  to  be  of 
one  kind.  Therefore  it  was  unfitting  to  make  a  distinction 
among  them,  so  that  it  was  forbidden  to  eat  the  flesh  of 
certain  peace-offerings  on  the  following  day,  while  it  was 
allowed  to  eat  the  flesh  of  other  peace-offerings,  as  laid 
down  in  Levit.  vii.  15,  seq. 

Obj.  II.  Further,  all  sins  agree  in  turning  us  from  God. 
Therefore,  in  order  to  reconcile  us  to  God,  one  kind  of 
sacrifice  should  have  been  offered  up  for  all  sins. 

Obj.  12.  Further,  all  animals  that  were  offered  up  in 
sacrifice,  were  offered  up  in  one  way,  viz.,  slain.  Therefore 
it  does  not  seem  to  be  suitable  that  products  of  the  soil 
should  be  offered  up  in  various  ways;  for  sometimes  an 
offering  was  made  of  ears  of  corn,  sometimes  of  flour,  some- 
times of  bread,  this  being  baked  sometimes  in  an  oven,  some- 
times in  a  pan,  sometimes  on  a  gridiron. 

Obj.  13.  Further,  whatever  things  are  serviceable  to  us 
should  be  recognized  as  coming  from  God.  It  was  there- 
fore unbecoming  that  besides  animals,  nothing  but  bread, 
wine,  oil,  incense,  and  salt  should  be  offered  to  God. 

Obj.  14.  Further,  bodily  sacrifices  denote  the  inward 
sacrifice  of  the  heart,  whereby  man  offers  his  soul  to  God. 
But  in  the  inward  sacrifice,  the  sweetness,  which  is  denoted 
by  honey,  surpasses  the  pungency  which  salt  represents ;  for 
it  is  written  (Ecclus.  xxiv.  27) :  My  spirit  is  sweet  above 
honey.  Therefore  it  was  unbecoming  that  the  use  of  honey, 
and  of  leaven  which  makes  bread  savoury,  should  be  for- 
bidden in  a  sacrifice;  while  the  use  was  prescribed,  of  salt 
which  is  pungent,  and  of  incense  which  has  a  bitter  taste. 
Consequently  it  seems  that  things  pertaining  to  the  cere- 
monies of  the  sacrifices  have  no  reasonable  cause. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Levit.  i.  13) :  The  priest  shall 


Q.  T02.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  166 

offer  it  all  and  hum  it  all  upon  the  altar,  for  a  holocaust,  and 
most  sweet  savour  to  the  Lord.  Now  according  to  Wis.  vii.  28, 
God  loveth  none  hut  him  that  dwelleth  with  wisdom  :  whence  it 
seems  to  follow  that  whatever  is  acceptable  to  God  is  wisely 
done.  Therefore  these  ceremonies  of  the  sacrifices  were 
wisely  done,  as  having  reasonable  causes. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  2),  the  ceremonies  of 
the  Old  Law  had  a  twofold  cause,  viz.,  a  literal  cause, 
according  as  they  were  intended  for  Divine  worship;  and  a 
figurative  or  mystical  cause,  according  as  they  were  intended 
to  foreshadow  Christ:  and  on  either  hand  the  ceremonies 
pertaining  to  the  sacrifices  can  be  assigned  to  a  fitting 
cause. 

For,  according  as  the  ceremonies  of  the  sacrifices  were 
intended  for  the  divine  worship,  the  causes  of  the  sacrifices 
can  be  taken  in  two  ways.  First,  in  so  far  as  the  sacrifice 
represented  the  directing  of  the  mind  to  God,  to  which  the 
offerer  of  the  sacrifice  was  stimulated.  Now  in  order  to 
direct  his  mind  to  God  aright,  man  must  recognize  that 
whatever  he  has  is  from  God  as  from  its  first  principle,  and 
direct  it  to  God  as  its  last  end.  This  was  denoted  in  the 
offerings  and  sacrifices,  by  the  fact  that  man  offered  some 
of  his  own  belongings  in  honour  of  God,  as  though  in  recog- 
nition of  his  having  received  them  from  God,  according  to 
the  saying  of  David  (i  Paral.  xxix.  14) :  All  things  are  Thine  : 
and  we  have  given  Thee  what  we  received  of  Thy  hand.  Where- 
fore in  offering  up  sacrifices  man  made  protestation  that 
God  is  the  first  principle  of  the  creation  of  all  things,  and 
their  last  end,  to  which  all  things  must  be  directed. — And 
since,  for  the  human  mind  to  be  directed  to  God  aright,  it 
must  recognize  no  first  author  of  things  other  than  God, 
nor  place  its  end  in  any  other;  for  this  reason  it  was  for- 
bidden in  the  Law  to  offer  sacrifice  to  any  other  but  God, 
according  to  Exod.  xxii.  20:  He  that  sacrificeth  to  gods,  shall 
he  put  to  death,  save  only  to  the  Lord.  Wherefore  another 
reasonable  cause  may  be  assigned  to  the  ceremonies  of  the 
sacrifices,  from  the  fact  that  thereby  men  were  withdrawn 
from  offering  sacrifices  to  idols.     Hence  too  it  is  that  the 


i6y  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  3 

precepts  about  the  sacrifices  were  not  given  to  the  Jewish 
people  until  after  they  had  fallen  into  idolatry,  by  wor- 
shipping the  molten  calf:  as  though  those  sacrifices  were 
instituted,  that  the  people,  being  ready  to  offer  sacrifices, 
might  offer  those  sacrifices  to  God  rather  than  to  idols. 
Thus  it  is  written  (Jer.  vii.  22) :  /  spake  not  to  your  fathers 
and  I  commanded  them  not,  in  the  day  that  I  brought  them 
out  of  the  land  of  Egypt,  concerning  the  matter  of  burnt- 
offerings  and  sacrifices. 

Now  of  all  the  gifts  which  God  vouchsafed  to  mankind 
after  they  had  fallen  away  by  sin,  the  chief  is  that  He  gave 
His  Son;  wherefore  it  is  written  (John  iii.  16) :  God  so  loved 
the  world,  as  to  give  His  only-begotten  Son  ;  that  whosoever 
believeth  in  Him,  may  not  perish,  but  may  have  life  everlasting. 
Consequently  the  chief  sacrifice  is  that  whereby  Christ 
Himself  delivered  Himself  .  .  .  to  God  for  an  odour  of  sweet- 
ness (Eph.  V.  2).  And  for  this  reason  all  the  other  sacri- 
fices of  the  Old  Law  were  offered  up  in  order  to  foreshadow 
this  one  individual  and  paramount  sacrifice, — the  imperfect 
forecasting  the  perfect.  Hence  the  Apostle  says  (Heb. 
X.  11)  that  the  priest  of  the  Old  Law  often  offered  the  same 
sacrifices,  ivhich  can  never  take  away  sins  :  but  Christ  offered 
one  sacrifice  for  sins,  for  ever.  And  since  the  reason  of  the 
figure  is  taken  from  that  which  the  figure  represents,  there- 
fore the  reasons  of  the  figurative  sacrifices  of  the  Old  Law 
should  be  taken  from  the  true  sacrifice  of  Christ. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  God  did  not  wish  these  sacrifices  to  be 
offered  to  Him  on  account  of  the  things  themselves  that 
were  offered,  as  though  He  stood  in  need  of  them:  where- 
fore it  is  written  (Isa.  i.  11) :  I  desire  not  holocausts  of  rams ^ 
and  fat  of  fallings,  and  blood  of  calves  and  lambs  and  buck- 
goats.  But,  as  stated  above.  He  wished  them  to  be  offered 
to  Him,  in  order  to  prevent  idolatry; — in  order  to  signify 
the  right  ordering  of  man's  mind  to  God; — and  in  order 
to  represent  the  mystery  of  the  Redemption  of  man  by 
Christ. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  In  all  the  respects  mentioned  above  {ad  i), 
there  was  a  suitable  reason  for  these  animals,  rather  than 


Q.  I02.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  168 

others,  being  offered  up  in  sacrifice  to  God.  First,  in  order 
to  prevent  idolatry.  Because  idolaters  offered  all  other 
animals  to  their  gods,  or  made  use  of  them  in  their  sor- 
ceries: while  the  Egyptians  (among  whom  the  people  had 
been  dwelling)  considered  it  abominable  to  slay  these 
animals,  wherefore  they  used  not  to  offer  them  in  sacrifice 
to  their  gods.  Hence  it  is  written  (Exod.  viii.  26) :  We  shall 
sacrifice  the  abominations  of  the  Egyptians  to  the  Lord  our  God. 
For  they  worshipped  the  sheep ;  they  reverenced  the  ram 
(because  demons  appeared  under  the  form  thereof) ;  while 
they  employed  oxen  for  agriculture,  which  was  reckoned  by 
them  as  something  sacred. 

Secondly,  this  was  suitable  for  the  aforesaid  right  order- 
ing of  man's  mind  to  God:  and  in  two  ways. — First,  because 
it  is  chiefly  by  means  of  these  animals  that  human  life  is 
sustained:  and  moreover  they  are  most  clean,  and  partake 
of  a  most  clean  food :  whereas  other  animals  are  either  wild, 
and  not  deputed  to  ordinary  use  among  men:  or,  if  they 
be  tame,  they  have  unclean  food,  as  pigs  and  geese :  and 
nothing  but  what  is  clean  should  be  offered  to  God. — These 
birds  especially  were  offered  in  sacrifice,  because  there  were 
plenty  of  them  in  the  land  of  promise. — Secondly,  because 
the  sacrificing  of  these  animals  represented  purity  of  heart. 
Because  as  the  gloss  says  on  Levit.  i..  We  offer  a  calf,  when 
we  overcome  the  pride  of  the  flesh  ;  a  lamb,  when  we  restrain 
our  unreasonable  motions ;  a  goat,  when  we  conquer  our 
wantonness  ;  a  turtledove,  when  we  keep  chaste  ;  unleavened 
bread,  when  we  feast  on  the  unleavened  bread  of  sincerity. 
And  it  is  evident  that  the  dove  denotes  charity  and  sim- 
plicity of  heart. 

Thirdly,  it  was  fitting  that  these  animals  should  be 
offered,  that  they  might  foreshadow  Christ.  Because,  as 
the  same  gloss  observes,  Christ  is  offered  in  the  calf,  to  denote 
the  strength  of  the  cross  ;  in  the  lamb,  to  signify  His  innocence  ; 
in  the  ram,  to  foreshadow  His  Headship  ;  in  the  goat,  to  signify 
the  likeness  of  '  sinful  flesh. "^^  The  turtledove  and  dove 
denoted  the  union  of  the  two  natures  ;  or  else  the  turtledove 

*  An  allusion  to  Col.  ii.  11  {Textus  Receptus). 


i69  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  3 

signified  chastity;  while  the  dove  was  a  figure  of  charity. 
The  wheat-flour  foreshadowed  the  sprinkling  of  believers  with 
the  water  of  Baptism. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Fish  through  Hving  in  water  are  further 
removed  from  man  than  other  animals,  which,  Hke  man, 
live  in  the  air.  Again,  fish  die  as  soon  as  they  are  taken 
out  of  water;  hence  they  could  not  be  offered  in  the  temple 
like  other  animals. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  Among  turtledoves  the  older  ones  are 
better  than  the  young;  while  with  doves  the  case  is  the 
reverse.  Wherefore,  as  Rabbi  Moses  observes  (Doctr.  Per- 
plex., iii.),  turtledoves  and  young  doves  are  commanded  to 
be  offered,  because  nothing  should  be  offered  to  God  but 
what  is  best. 

Reply  Ohj.  5.  The  animals  which  were  offered  in  sacrifice 
were  slain,  because  it  is  by  being  killed  that  they  become 
useful  to  man,  forasmuch  as  God  gave  them  to  man  for 
food.  Wherefore  also  they  were  burnt  with  fire :  because  it 
is  by  being  cooked  that  they  are  made  fit  for  human  con- 
sumption.— Moreover  the  slaying  of  the  animals  signified 
the  destruction  of  sins:  and  also  that  man  deserved  death 
on  account  of  his  sins;  as  though  those  animals  were  slain 
in  man's  stead,  in  order  to  betoken  the  expiation  of  sins. 
— Again  the  slaying  of  these  animals  signified  the  slaying 
of  Christ. 

Reply  Ohj.  6.  The  Law  fixed  the  special  manner  of  slay- 
ing the  sacrificial  animals  in  order  to  exclude  other  ways 
of  killing,  whereby  idolaters  sacrificed  animals  to  idols. — 
Or  again,  as  Rabbi  Moses  says  [loc.  cit.),  the  Law  chose  that 
manner  of  slaying  which  was  least  painful  to  the  slain  animal. 
This  excluded  cruelty  on  the  part  of  the  offerers,  and  any 
mangling  of  the  animals  slain. 

Reply  Ohj.  7.  It  is  because  unclean  animals  are  wont  to 
be  held  in  contempt  among  men,  that  it  was  forbidden  to 
offer  thern  in  sacrifice  to  God:  and  for  this  reason  too  they 
were  forbidden  (Deut.  xxiii.  18)  to  offer  ^A^  hire  of  a  strumpet 
or  the  price  of  a  dog  in  the  house  of  .  .  .  God.  For  the  same 
reason  they  did  not  offer  animals  before  the  seventh  day, 


Q.  T02.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  170 

because  such  were  abortive  as  it  were,  the  flesh  being  not 
yet  firm  on  account  of  its  exceeding  softness. 

Reply  Obj.  8.  There  were  three  kinds  of  sacrifices.  There 
was  one  in  which  the  victim  was  entirely  consumed  by  fire : 
this  was  called  a  holocaust,  i.e.,  all  burnt.  For  this  kind  of 
sacrifice  was  offered  to  God  specially  to  show  reverence  to 
His  majesty,  and  love  of  His  goodness:  and  typified  the 
state  of  perfection  as  regards  the  fulfilment  of  the  counsels. 
Wherefore  the  whole  was  burnt  up:  so  that  as  the  whole 
animal  by  being  dissolved  into  vapour  soared  aloft,  so  it 
might  denote  that  the  whole  man,  and  whatever  belongs  to 
him,  are  subject  to  the  authority  of  God,  and  should  be 
offered  to  Him. 

Another  sacrifice  was  the  sin-offering,  .which  was  offered 
to  God  on  account  of  man's  need  for  the  forgiveness  of 
sin:  and  this  typifies  the  state  of  penitents  in  satisfying 
for  sins.  It  was  divided  into  two  parts:  for  one  part  was 
burnt;  while  the  other  was  granted  to  the  use  of  the 
priests  to  signify  that  remission  of  sins  is  granted  b}^  God 
through  the  ministry  of  His  priests.  When,  however,  this 
sacrifice  was  offered  for  the  sins  of  the  whole  people,  or 
specially  for  the  sin  of  the  priest,  the  whole  victim  was 
burnt  up.  For  it  was  not  fitting  that  the  priests  should 
have  the  use  of  that  which  was  offered  for  their  own  sins, 
to  signify  that  nothing  sinful  should  remain  in  them. 
Moreover,  this  would  not  be  satisfaction  for  sin:  for  if  the 
offering  were  granted  to  the  use  of  those  for  whose  sins  it 
was  offered,  it  would  seem  to  be  the  same  as  if  it  had  not 
been  offered. 

The  third  kind  of  sacrifice  was  called  the  peace-offering, 
which  was  offered  to  God,  either  in  thanksgiving,  or  for  the 
welfare  and  prosperity  of  the  offerers,  in  acknowledgment 
of  benefits  already  received  or  yet  to  be  received :  and  this 
typifies  the  state  of  those  who  are  proficient  in  the  obser- 
vance of  the  commandments.  These  sacrifices  were  divided 
into  three  parts :  for  one  part  was  burnt  in  honour  of  God ; 
another  part  was  allotted  to  the  use  of  the  priests;  and 
the   third  1  part   to  the  use   of  the   offerers ;   in   order  to 


171  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  3 

signify  that  man's  salvation  is  from  God,  by  the  direction 
of  God's  ministers,  and  through  the  co-operation  of  those 
who  are  saved. 

But  it  was  the  universal  rule  that  the  blood  and  fat  were 
not  allotted  to  the  use  either  of  the  priests  or  of  the  offerers : 
the  blood  being  poured  out  at  the  foot  of  the  altar,  in 
honour  of  God,  while  the  fat  was  burnt  upon  the  altar 
(Levit.  ix.  9,  10).  The  reason  for  this  was,  first,  in  order 
to  prevent  idolatry:  because  idolaters  used  to  drink  the 
blood  and  eat  the  fat  of  the  victims,  according  to  Deut. 
xxxii.  38 :  Of  whose  victims  they  eat  the  fat,  and  drank  the 
wine  of  their  drink-offerings. — Secondly,  in  order  to  form 
them  to  a  right  way  of  living.  For  they  were  forbidden 
the  use  of  the  blood  that  they  might  abhor  the  shedding 
of  human  blood;  wherefore  it  is  written  (Gen.  ix.  4,  5): 
Flesh  with  Mood  you  shall  not  eat  :  for  I  will  require  the  blood 
of  your  lives  : — and  they  were  forbidden  to  eat  the  fat,  in 
order  to  withdraw  them  from  lasciviousness ;  hence  it  is 
written  (Ezech.  xxxiv.  3) :  You  have  killed  that  which  was 
fat. — Thirdly,  on  account  of  the  reverence  due  to  God: 
because  blood  is  most  necessary  for  life,  for  which  reason 
I  fe  is  said  to  be  in  the  blood  (Levit.  xvii.  11,  14):  while  fat 
is  a  sign  of  abundant  nourishment.  Wherefore,  in  order  to 
show  that  to  God  we  owe  both  life  and  a  sufficiency  of  all 
good  things,  the  blood  was  poured  out,  and  the  fat  burnt 
up  in  His  honour. — Fourthly,  in  order  to  foreshadow  the 
shedding  of  Christ's  blood,  and  the  abundance  of  His  charity, 
whereby  He  offered  Himself  to  God  for  us. 

In  the  peace-offerings,  the  breast-bone  and  the  right 
shoulder  were  allotted  to  the  use  of  the  priest,  in  order 
to  prevent  a  certain  kind  of  divination  which  is  known 
as  spatulamantia,  so  called  because  it  was  customary  in 
divining  to  use  the  shoulder-blade  {spatula),  and  the 
breast-bone  of  the  animals  offered  in  sacrifice;  wherefore 
these  things  were  taken  away  from  the  offerers. — This 
also  denoted  the  priest's  need  of  wisdom  in  the  heart,  to 
instruct  the  people, — this  was  signified  by  the  breast-bone, 
which  covers  the  heart;  and  his  need  of  fortitude,  in  order 


Q.  I02.  Art.  3      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  172 

to  bear  with  human  frailty — and  this  was  signified  by  the 
right  shoulder. 

Reply  Ohj.  9.  Because  the  holocaust  was  the  most  perfect 
kind  of  sacrifice,  therefore  none  but  a  male  was  offered  for 
a  holocaust:  because  the  female  is  an  imperfect  animal. — 
The  offering  of  turtledoves  and  doves  was  on  account  of  the 
poverty  of  the  offerers,  who  were  unable  to  offer  bigger 
animals.  And  since  peace-victims  were  offered  freely,  and 
no  one  was  bound  to  offer  them  against  his  will,  hence 
these  birds  were  offered  not  among  the  peace-victims,  but 
among  the  holocausts  and  victims  for  sin,  which  man  was 
obliged  to  offer  at  times.  Moreover  these  birds,  on  account 
of  their  lofty  flight,  were  befitting  the  perfection  of  the 
holocausts:  and  were  suitable  for  sin-offerings,  because  their 
song  is  doleful. 

Reply  Ohj.  10.  The  holocaust  was  the  chief  of  all  the 
sacrifices:  because  all  was  burnt  in  honour  of  God,  and 
nothing  of  it  was  eaten.  The  second  place  in  holiness, 
belongs  to  the  sacrifice  for  sins,  which  was  eaten  in  the 
court  only,  and  on  the  very  day  of  the  sacrifice  (Lev.  vii .  6, 
15).  The  third  place  must  be  given  to  the  peace-offerings 
of  thanksgiving,  which  were  eaten  on  the  same  day,  but 
anywhere  in  Jerusalem.  Fourth  in  order  were  the  ex-voto 
peace-offerings,  the  flesh  of  which  could  be  eaten  even  on 
the  morrow.  The  reason  for  this  order  is  that  man  is  bound 
to  God,  chiefly  on  account  of  His  majesty;  secondly,  on 
account  of  the  sins  he  has  committed;  thirdly,  because  of 
the  benefits  he  has  already  received  from  Him;  fourthly,  by 
reason  of  the  benefits  he  hopes  to  receive  from  Him. 

Reply  Ohj.  11.  Sins  are  more  grievous  by  reason  of  the 
state  of  the  sinner,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXHL,  A.  10): 
wherefore  different  victims  are  commanded  to  be  offered 
for  the  sin  of  a  priest,  or  of  a  prince,  or  of  some  other  private 
individual.  But,  as  Rabbi  Moses  says,  we  must  take  note 
that  the  more  grievous  the  sin,  the  lower  the  species  of  animal 
offered  for  it.  Wherefore  the  goat,  which  is  a  very  hase  animal , 
was  offered  for  idolatry  ;  while  a  calf  was  offered  for  a  priest's 
ignorance,  and  a  ram  for  the  negligence  of  a  prince. 


173  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS    Q.  102.  Art.  3 

Reply  Obj.  12.  In  the  matter  of  sacrifices  the  Law  had  in 
view  the  poverty  of  the  offerers;  so  that  those  who  could 
not  have  a  four-footed  animal  at  their  disposal,  might  at 
least  offer  a  bird;  and  that  he  who  could  not  have  a  bird 
might  at  least  offer  bread;  and  that  if  a  man  had  not  even 
bread  he  might  offer  flour  or  ears  of  corn. 

The  figurative  cause  is  that  the  bread  signifies  Christ 
Who  is  the  living  bread  (John  vi.  41,  51).  He  was  indeed 
an  ear  of  corn,  as  it  were,  during  the  state  of  the  law  of 
nature,  in  the  faith  of  the  patriarchs;  He  was  like  flour  in 
the  doctrine  of  the  Law  of  the  prophets;  and  He  was  like 
perfect  bread  after  He  had  taken  human  nature;  baked  in 
the  fire,  i.e.,  formed  by  the  Holy^  Ghost  in  the  oven  of  the 
virginal  womb;  baked  again  in  a  pan  by  the  toils  which  He 
suffered  in  the  world;  and  consumed  by  fire  on  the  cross  as 
on  a  gridiron. 

Reply  Obj.  13.  The  products  of  the  soil  are  useful  to  man, 
either  as  food,  and  of  these  bread  was  offered;  or  as  drink, 
and  of  these  wine  was  offered;  or  as  seasoning,  and  of  these 
oil  and  salt  were  offered;  or  as  healing,  and  of  these  they 
offered  incense,  which  both  smells  sweetly  and  binds  easily 
together. 

Now  the  bread  foreshadowed  the  flesh  of  Christ ;  and  the 
wine.  His  blood,  whereby  we  were  redeemed;  oil  betokens 
the  grace  of  Christ;  salt.  His  knowledge;  incense.  His 
prayer. 

Reply  Obj.  14.  Honey  was  not  offered  in  the  sacrifices  to 
God,  both  because  it  was  wont  to  be  offered  in  the  sacrifices 
to  idols;  and  in  order  to  denote  the  absence  of  all  carnal 
sweetness  and  pleasure  from  those  who  intend  to  sacrifice 
to  God. — 'Leaven  was  not  offered,  to  denote  the  exclusion 
of  corruption.  Perhaps  too,  it  was  wont  to  be  offered  in 
the  sacrifices  to  idols. 

Salt,  however,  was  offered,  because  it  wards  off  the  cor- 
ruption of  putrefaction :  for  sacrifices  offered  to  God  should 
be  incorrupt.  Moreover,  salt  signifies  the  discretion  of 
wisdom,  or  again,  mortification  of  the  flesh. 

Incense  was  offered  to  denote  devotion  of  the  heart,  which 


Q.  I02.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  ''  174 

is  necessary  in  the  offerer;  and  again,  to  signify  the  odour 
of  a  good  name:  for  incense  is  composed  of  matter,  both 
rich  and  fragrant.  And  since  the  sacrifice  of  jealousy  did 
not  proceed  from  devotion,  but  rather  from  suspicion, 
therefore  incense  was  not  offered  therein  (Num.  v.  15). 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  sufficient  reason  can  be  assigned  for  the 
ceremonies  pertaining  to  holy  things  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  :  — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  no  sufficient  reason  can  be 
assigned  for  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law  that  pertain  to 
holy  things.  For  Paul  said  (Acts  xvii.  24) :  God  Who  made 
the  world  and  all  things  therein  ;  He  being  Lord  of  heaven 
and  earth,  dwelleth  not  in  temples  made  by  hands.  It  was 
therefore  unfitting  that  in  the  Old  Law  a  tabernacle  or 
temple  should  be  set  up  for  the  worship  of  God. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  state  of  the  Old  Law  was  not  changed 
except  by  Christ.  But  the  tabernacle  denoted  the  state  of 
the  Old  Law.  Therefore  it  should  not  have  been  changed 
by  the  building  of  a  temple. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Divine  law,  more  than  any  other 
indeed,  should  lead  man  to  the  worship  of  God.  But  an 
increase  of  divine  worship  requires  multiplication  of  altars 
and  temples;  as  is  evident  in  regard  to  the  New  Law. 
Therefore  it  seems  that  also  under  the  Old  Law  there  should 
have  been  not  only  one  tabernacle  or  temple,  but  many. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  the  tabernacle  or  temple  was  ordained 
to  the  worship  of  God.  But  in  God  we  should  worship 
above  all  His  unity  and  simplicity.  Therefore  it  seems 
unbecoming  for  the  tabernacle  or  temple  to  be  divided  by 
means  of  veils. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  the  power  of  the  First  Mover,  i.e.,  God, 
appears  first  of  all  in  the  east,  for  it  is  in  that  quarter  that 
the  first  movement  begins.  But  the  tabernacle  was  set  up 
for  the  worship  of  God.  Therefore  it  should  have  been 
built  so  as  to  point  to  the  east  rather  than  the  west. 


175  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  4 

Obj.  6.  Further,  the  Lord  commanded  (Exod.  xx.  4)  that 
they  should  not  make  .  .  .  a  graven  thing,  nor  the  likeness 
of  anything.  It  was  therefore  unfitting  for  graven  images 
of  the  cherubim  to  be  set  up  in  the  tabernacle  or  temple. 
In  like  manner  the  ark,  the  propitiatory,  the  candlestick, 
the  table,  the  two  altars,  seem  to  have  been  placed  there 
without  reasonable  cause. 

Ohj.  7.  Further,  the  Lord  commanded  (Exod.  xx.  24) : 
You  shall  make  an  altar  of  earth  unto  Me :  and  again  {ibid., 
26) :  Thou  shalt  not  go  up  by  steps  unto  My  altar.  It  was 
therefore  unfitting  that  subsequently  they  should  be  com- 
manded to  make  an  altar  of  wood  laid  over  with  gold  or 
brass;  and  of  such  a  height  that  it  was  impossible  to  go  up 
to  it  except  by  steps.  For  it  is  written  (Exod.  xxvii.  1,2): 
Thou  shalt  make  also  an  altar  of  setim  wood,  which  shall  be 
five  cubits  long,  and  as  many  broad,  .  .  .  and  three  cubits 
high  .  .  .  and  thou  shalt  cover  it  with  brass  :  and  (Exod. 
XXX.  1,3):  Thou  shalt  make  .  .  .  an  altar  to  burn  incense, 
of  setim  wood  .  .  .  and  thou  shall  overlay  it  with  the  purest 
gold. 

Obj.  8.  Further,  in  God's  works  nothing  should  be  super- 
fluous; for  not  even  in  the  works  of  nature  is  anything 
superfluous  to  be  found.  But  one  cover  suffices  for  one 
tabernacle  or  house.  Therefore  it  was  unbecoming  to 
furnish  the  tabernacle  with  many  coverings,  viz.,  curtains, 
curtains  of  goats'  hair,  rams'  skins  dyed  red,  and  violet- 
coloured  skins  (Exod.  xxvi.). 

Obj.  9.  Further,  exterior  consecration  signifies  interior 
holiness,  the  subject  of  which  is  the  soul.  It  was  therefore 
unsuitable  for  the  tabernacle  and  its  vessels  to  be  conse- 
crated, since  they  were  inanimate  things. 

Obj.  10.  Further,  it  is  written  (Ps.  xxxiii.  2) :  /  will  bless 
the  Lord  at  all  times,  His  praise  shall  always  be  in  my  mouth. 
But  the  solemn  festivals  were  instituted  for  the  praise  of 
God.  Therefore  it  was  not  fitting  that  certain  days  should 
be  fixed  for  keeping  solemn  festivals;  so  that  it  seems  that 
there  was  no  suitable  cause  for  the  ceremonies  relating  to 
holy  things. 


Q.  I02.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  176 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Heb.  viii.  4)  that  those 
who  offer  gifts  according  to  the  law,  .  .  .  serve  unto  the 
example  and  shadow  of  heavenly  things.  As  it  was  answered 
to  Moses,  when  he  was  to  finish  the  tabernacle :  See,  says  He, 
that  thou  make  all  things  according  to  the  pattern  which  was 
shown  thee  on  the  mount.  But  that  is  most  reasonable, 
which  presents  a  likeness  to  heavenly  things.  Therefore  the 
ceremonies  relating  to  holy  things  had  a  reasonable  cause. 

I  answer  that,  The  chief  purpose  of  the  whole  external 
worship  is  that  man  may  give  worship  to  God.  Now  man's 
tendency  is  to  reverence  less  those  things  which  are  com- 
mon, and  indistinct  from  other  things ;  whereas  he  admires 
and  reveres  those  things  which  are  distinct  from  others  in 
some  point  of  excellence.  Hence  too  it  is  customary  among 
men  for  kings  and  princes,  who  ought  to  be  reverenced  by 
their  subjects,  to  be  clothed  in  more  precious  garments,  and 
to  possess  vaster  and  more  beautiful  abodes.  And  for  this 
reason  it  behoved  special  times,  a  special  abode,  special 
vessels,  and  special  ministers  to  be  appointed  for  the  divine 
worship,  so  that  thereby  the  soul  of  man  might  be  brought 
to  greater  reverence  for  God. 

In  like  manner  the  state  of  the  Old  Law,  as  observed 
above  (A.  2;  Q.  C,  A.  12;  Q.  CI.,  A.  2),  was  instituted  that 
it  might  foreshadow  the  mystery  of  Christ.  Nov^  that 
which  foreshadows  something  should  be  determinate,  so 
that  it  may  present  some  likeness  thereto.  Consequently, 
certain  special  points  had  to  be  observed  in  matters  per- 
taining to  the  worship  of  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  divine  worship  regards  two  things: 
namely,  God  Who  is  worshipped;  and  men,  who  worship 
Him.  Accordingly  God,  Who  is  worshipped,  is  confined  to 
no  bodily  place:  wherefore  there  was  no  need,  on  His  part, 
for  a  tabernacle  or  temple  to  be  set  up.  But  men,  who 
worship  Him,  are  corporeal  beings:  and  for  their  sake  there 
was  need  for  a  special  tabernacle  or  temple  to  be  set  up 
for  the  worship  of  God,  for  two  reasons.  First,  that  through 
coming  together  with  the  thought  that  the  place  was 
set  aside  for  the  worship  of  God,   they  might  approach 


177  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  4 

thither  with  greater  reverence.  Secondly,  that  certain 
things  relating  to  the  excellence  of  Christ's  Divine  or 
human  nature  might  be  signified  by  the  arrangement  of 
various  details  in  such  temple  or  tabernacle. 

To  this  Solomon  refers  (3  Kings  viii.  27)  when  he  says: 
//  heaven  and  the  heavens  of  heavens  cannot  contain  Thee, 
how  much  less  this  house  which  I  have  built  for  Thee  ?  And 
further  on  {ibid.  29,  30)  he  adds:  That  Thy  eyes  may  be 
open  upon  this  house  .  .  .  of  which  Thou  hast  said :  My 
name  shall  be  there  ;  .  .  .  that  Thou  mayest  hearken  to  the 
siipplication  of  Thy  servant  and  of  Thy  people  Israel.  From 
this  it  is  evident  that  the  house  of  the  sanctuary  was  set 
up,  not  in  order  to  contain  God,  as  abiding  therein  locally, 
but  that  God's  name  might  dwell  there,  i.e.,  that  God  might 
be  made  known  there  by  means  of  things  done  and  said 
there;  and  that  those  who  prayed  there  might,  through 
reverence  for  the  place,  pray  more  devoutly,  so  as  to  be 
heard  more  readily. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Before  the  coming  of  Christ,  the  state  of  the 
Old  Law  was  not  changed  as  regards  the  fulfilment  of  the 
Law,  which  was  effected  in  Christ  alone :  but  it  was  changed 
as  regards  the  condition  of  the  people  that  were  under  the 
Law.  Because,  at  first,  the  people  were  in  the  desert, 
having  no  fixed  abode:  afterwards  they  were  engaged  in 
various  wars  with  the  neighbouring  nations;  and  lastly,  at 
the  time  of  David  and  Solomon,  the  state  of  that  people 
was  one  of  great  peace.  And  then  for  the  first  time  the 
temple  was  built  in  the  place  which  Abraham,  instructed 
by  God,  had  chosen  for  the  purpose  of  sacrifice.  For  it  is 
written  (Gen.  xxii.  2)  that  the  Lord  commanded  Abraham 
to  offer  his  son  for  a  holocaust  upon  one  of  the  mountains 
which  I  will  show  thee  :  and  it  is  related  further  on  [ibid.  14) 
that  he  called  the  name  of  that  place,  The  Lord  seeth,  as  though, 
according  to  the  Divine  prevision,  that  place  were  chosen 
for  the  worship  of  God.  Hence  it  is  written  (Deut.  xii.  5,  6) : 
You  shall  come  to  the  place  which  the  Lord  your  God  shall 
choose  .  .  .  and  you  shall  offer  .  .  .  your  holocausts  and 
victims. 
II.  3  12 


Q.  102.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  178 

Now  it  was  not  meet  for  that  place  to  be  pointed  out  by 
the  building  of  the  temple  before  the  aforesaid  time;  for 
three  reasons  assigned  by  Rabbi  Moses.  First,  lest  the 
Gentiles  might  seize  hold  of  that  place.  Secondly,  lest  the 
Gentiles  might  destroy  it.  The  third  reason  is  lest  each 
tribe  might  wish  that  place  to  fall  to  their  lot,  and  strifes 
and  quarrels  be  the  result.  Hence  the  temple  was  not 
built  until  they  had  a  king  who  would  be  able  to  quell 
such  quarrels.  Until  that  time  a  portable  tabernacle  was 
employed  for  divine  worship,  no  place  being  as  yet 
lixed  for  the  worship  of  God.  This  is  the  literal 
reason  for  the  distinction  between  the  tabernacle  and 
the  temple. 

The  figurative  reason  may  be  assigned  to  the  fact  that 
they  signify  a  twofold  state.  For  the  tabernacle,  which 
was  changeable,  signifies  the  state  of  the  present  changeable 
life:  whereas  the  temple,  which  was  fixed  and  stable,  sig- 
nifies the  state  of  future  life  which  is  altogether  unchange- 
able. For  this  reason  it  is  said  that  in  the  building  of  the 
temple  no  sound  was  heard  of  hammer  or  saw,  to  signify 
that  all  movements  of  disturbance  will  be  far  removed  from 
the  future  state. — Or  else  the  tabernacle  signifies  the  state 
of  the  Old  Law;  while  the  temple  built  by  Solomon  betokens 
the  state  of  the  New  Law.  Hence  the  Jews  alone  worked  at 
the  building  of  the  tabernacle;  whereas  the  temple  was 
built  with  the  co-operation  of  the  Gentiles,  viz.,  the  Tyrians 
and  Sidonians. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  reason  for  the  unity  of  the  temple  or 
tabernacle  may  be  either  literal  or  figurative.  The  literal 
reason  was  the  exclusion  of  idolatry.  For  the  Gentiles  put 
up  various  temples  to  various  gods:  and  so,  to  strengthen 
in  the  minds  of  men  their  belief  in  the  unity  of  the  God- 
head, God  wished  sacrifices  to  be  offered  to  Him  in  one 
place  only. — ^Another  reason  was  in  order  to  show  that 
bodily  worship  is  not  acceptable  of  itself :  and  so  they  were 
restrained  from  offering  sacrifices  anywhere  and  every- 
where. But  the  worship  of  the  New  Law,  in  the  sacrifice 
whereof  spiritual  grace  is  contained,  is  of  itself  acceptable 


179  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS       Q.  102.  Akt.  4 

to  God;  and  consequently  the  multiplication  of   altars  and 
temples  is  permitted  in  the  New  Law. 

As  to  those  matters  that  regarded  the  spiritual  worship  of 
God,  consisting  in  the  teaching  of  the  Law  and  the  Prophets, 
there  were,  even  under  the  Old  Law,  various  places,  called 
synagogues,  appointed  for  the  people  to  gather  together 
for  the  praise  of  God;  just  as  now  there  are  places  called 
churches  in  which  the  Christian  people  gather  together 
for  the  divine  worship.  Thus  our  church  takes  the  place  of 
both  temple  and  synagogue :  since  the  very  sacrifice  of  the 
Church  is  spiritual;  wherefore  with  us  the  place  of  sacrifice 
is  not  distinct  from  the  place  of  teaching.  The  figurative 
reason  may  be  that  hereby  is  signified  the  unity  of  the 
Church,  whether  militant  or  triumphant. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  Just  as  the  unity  of  the  temple  or  taber- 
nacle betokened  the  unity  of  God,  or  the  unity  of  the  Church, 
so  also  the  division  of  the  tabernacle  or  temple  signified  the 
distinction  of  those  things  that  are  subject  to  God,  and  from 
which  we  arise  to  the  worship  of  God.  Now  the  tabernacle 
was  divided  into  two  parts:  one  was  called  the  Holy  of 
Holies,  and  was  placed  to  west  ;  the  other  was  called  the 
Holy  Place,"^  which  was  situated  to  the  east.  Moreover 
there  was  a  court  facing  the  tabernacle.  Accordingly  there 
are  two  reasons  for  this  distinction.  One  is  in  respect  of 
the  tabernacle  being  ordained  to  the  worship  of  God.  Be- 
cause the  different  parts  of  the  world  are  thus  betokened  by 
the  division  of  the  tabernacle.  For  that  part  which  was 
called  the  Holy  of  Holies  signified  the  higher  world,  which 
is  that  of  spiritual  substances:  while  that  part  which  is 
called  the  Holy  Place  signified  the  corporeal  world. — Hence 
the  Holy  Place  was  separated  from  the  Holy  of  Holies  by 
a  veil,  which  was  of  four  different  colours  (denoting  the  four 
elements),  viz.,  of  linen,  signifying  earth,  because  linen,  i.e., 
flax,  grows  out  of  the  earth;  purple,  signifying  water,  be- 
cause the  purple  tint  was  made  from  certain  shells  found 
in  the  sea;  violet,  signifying  air,  because  it  has  the  colour 
of  the  air;  and  scarlet  twice  dyed,  signifying  lire: — and  this 

*  Or  Sanctuary.     The  Douay  version  uses  both  expressions. 


Q.  102.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  180 

because  matter  composed  of  the  four  elements  is  a  veil 
between  us  and  incorporeal  substances.     Hence  the  high- 
priest  alone,  and  that  once  a  year,  entered  into  the  inner 
tabernacle,  i.e.,  the  Holy  of  Holies:  whereby  we  are  taught 
that  man's  final  perfection  consists  in  his  entering  into  that 
(higher)  world:  whereas  into  the  outward  tabernacle,  i.e., 
the  Holy  Place,   the  priests  entered  every  day :  whereas 
the  people  were  only  admitted  to  the  court ;   because  the 
people  are  able  to  perceive  material  things,  the  inner  nature 
of  which  only  wise  men  by  dint  of  study  are  able  to  discover. 
But  with  regard  to  the  figurative  reason,  the  outward 
tabernacle,  which  was  called  the  Holy  Place,  betokened 
the  state  of  the  Old  Law,  as  the  Apostle  says  (Heb.  ix.  6, 
seq.) :  because  into  that  tabernacle  the  priests  always  entered 
accomplishing  the  offices  of  sacrifices.     But  the  inner  taber- 
nacle, which  was  called  the  Holy  of  Holies,  signified  either 
the  glory  of  heaven  or  the  spiritual  state  of  the  New  Law, 
which  is  a  kind  of  beginning  of  the  glory  to  come.      To 
the  latter  state  Christ  brought  us;  and  this  was  signified 
by  the  high-priest  entering  alone,  once  a  year,  into  the  Holy 
of  Holies. — The  veil  betokened  the  concealing  of  the  spiri- 
tual sacrifices  under  the  sacrifices  of  old.     This  veil  was 
adorned  with  four  colours:  viz.,  that  of  linen,  to  designate 
purity  of  the  flesh;  purple,  to  denote  the  sufferings  which 
the  saints  underwent  for  God;  scarlet  twice  dyed,  signi- 
fying the  twofold  love  of  God  and  our  neighbour;  and  violet, 
in  token  of  heavenly  contemplation. — With  regard  to  the 
state  of  the  Old  Law  the  people  and  the  priests  were  situ- 
ated differently  from  one  another.     For  the  people  saw  the 
mere  corporeal  sacrifices  which  were  offered  in  the  court: 
whereas  the  priests  were  intent  on  the  inner  meaning  of  the 
sacrifices,  because  their  faith  in  the  mysteries  of  Christ  was 
more  explicit.    Hence  they  entered  into  the  outer  tabernacle. 
This  outer  tabernacle  was  divided  from  the  court  by  a  veil ; 
because  some  matters  relating  to  the  mystery  of  Christ 
were  hidden  from  the  people,  while  they  were  known  to  the 
priests:  though  they  were  not  fully  revealed  to  them,  as  they 
were  subsequently  in  the  New  Testament  {cf.  Ephes.  iii.  5). 


I 


i8i  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  4 

Reply  Obj.  5.  Worship  towards  the  west  was  introduced 
in  the  Law  to  the  exchision  of  idolatry:  because  all  the 
Gentiles,  in  reverence  to  the  sun,  worshipped  towards  the 
east  ;  hence  it  is  written  (Ezech.  viii.  16)  that  certain  men 
had  their  hacks  towards  the  temple  of  the  Lord,  and  their  faces 
to  the  east,  and  they  adored  towards  the  rising  of  the  sun. 
Accordingly,  in  order  to  prevent  this,  the  tabernacle  had  the 
Holy  of  Holies  to  westward,  that  they  might  adore  toward 
the  west.  A  figurative  reason  may  also  be  found  in  the  fact 
that  the  whole  state  of  the  first  tabernacle  was  ordained 
to  foreshadow  the  death  of  Christ,  which  is  signified  by  the 
west,  according  to  Ps.  Ixvii.  5:  Who  ascendeth  unto  the  west ; 
the  Lord  is  His  name. 

Reply  Obj.  6.  Both  literal  and  figurative  reasons  may  be 
assigned  for  the  things  contained  in  the  tabernacle.  The 
literal  reason  is  in  connection  with  the  divine  worship. 
And  because,  as  already  observed  {ad  4),  the  inner  tabernacle, 
called  the  Holy  of  Holies,  signified  the  higher  world  of 
spiritual  substances,  hence  that  tabernacle  contained  three 
things,  viz.,  the  ark  of  the  testament  in  which  was  a  golden 
pot  that  had  manna,  and  the  rod  of  Aaron  that  had  blossomed, 
and  the  tables  (Heb.  ix.  4)  on  which  were  written  the  ten 
commandments  of  the  Law.  Now  the  ark  stood  between 
two  cherubim  that  looked  one  towards  the  other:  and  over 
the  ark  was  a  table,  called  the  propitiatory,  raised  above  the 
wings  of  the  cherubim,  as  though  it  were  held  up  by  them; 
and  appearing,  to  the  imagination,  to  be  the  very  seat  of 
God.  For  this  reason  it  was  called  the  propitiatory,  as 
though  the  people  received  propitiation  thence  at  the  prayers 
of  the  high-priest.  And  so  it  was  held  up,  so  to  speak,  by 
the  cherubim,  in  obedience,  as  it  were,  to  God:  while  the 
ark  of  the  testament  was  like  the  foot-stool  to  Him  that 
sat  on  the  propitiatory. — These  three  things  denote  three 
things  in  that  higher  world:  namely,  God  Who  is  above 
all,  and  incomprehensible  to  any  creature.  Hence  no  like- 
ness of  Him  was  set  up;  to  denote  His  invisibility.  But 
there  was  something  to  represent  His  seat;  since,  to  wit, 
the  creature,  which  is  beneath  God,  as  the  seat  is  under  the 


Q.  I02.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  182 

sitter,  is  comprehensible. — Again  in  that  higher  world 
there  are  spiritual  substances  called  angels.  These  are 
signified  by  the  two  cherubim,  looking  one  towards  the  other, 
to  show  that  they  are  at  peace  with  one  another,  according 
to  Job  XXV.  2:  Who  maketh  peace  in  .  .  .  high  places.  For 
this  reason,  too,  there  was  more  than  one  cherub,  to  betoken 
the  multitude  of  heavenly  spirits,  and  to  prevent  their 
receiving  worship  from  those  who  had  been  commanded  to 
worship  but  one  God. — Moreover  there  are,  enclosed  as  it 
were  in  that  spiritual  world,  the  intelligible  types  of  what- 
soever takes  place  in  this  world,  just  as  in  every  cause  are 
enclosed  the  types  of  its  effects,  and  in  the  craftsman  the 
types  of  the  works  of  his  craft.  This  was  betokened  by  the 
ark,  which  represented,  by  means  of  the  three  things  it 
contained,  the  three  things  of  greatest  import  in  human 
affairs.  These  are  wisdom,  signified  by  the  tables  of  the 
testament;  the  power  of  governing,  betokened  by  the  rod 
of  Aaron;  and  life,  denoted  by  the  manna  which  was  the 
means  of  sustenance. — Or  else  these  three  signified  the  three 
Divine  attributes,  viz.,  wisdom,  in  the  tables;  power,  in 
the  rod;  goodness,  in  the  manna, — both  by  reason  of  its 
sweetness,  and  because  it  was  through  the  goodness  of  God 
that  it  was  granted  to  man,  wherefore  it  was  preserved  as 
a  memorial  of  the  Divine  mercy. — Again,  these  three  things 
were  represented  in  Isaias'  vision.  For  he  saw  the  Lord 
sitting  upon  a  throne  high  and  elevated  ;  and  the  seraphim 
standing  by;  and  that  the  house  was  filled  with  the  glory 
of  the  Lord;  wherefore  the  seraphim  cried  out  :  All  the 
earth  is  full  of  His  glory  (Isa.  vi.  i,  3). — And  so  the  images 
of  the  seraphim  were  set  up,  not  to  be  worshipped,  for  this 
was  forbidden  by  the  first  commandment;  but  as  a  sign  of 
their  function,  as  stated  above. 

The  outer  tabernacle,  which  denotes  this  present  world, 
also  contained  three  things,  viz.,  the  altar  of  incense,  which 
was  directly  opposite  the  ark;  the  table  of  proposition,  with 
the  twelve  loaves  of  proposition  on  it,  which  stood  on  the 
northern  side ;  and  the  candlestick,  which  was  placed  towards 
the  south.     These  three  things  seem  to  correspond  to  the 


i83  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  4 

three  which  were  enclosed  in  the  ark;  and  they  represented 
the  same  things  as  the  latter,  but  more  clearly:  because, 
in  order  that  wise  men,  denoted  by  the  priests  entering 
the  temple,  might  grasp  the  meaning  of  these  types,  it  was 
necessary  to  express  them  more  manifestly  than  they  are  in 
the  Divine  or  angelic  mind. — Accordingly  the  candlestick 
betokened,  as  a  sensible  sign  thereof,  the  wisdom  which  was 
expressed  on  the  tables  (of  the  Law)  in  intelligible  words. — 
The  altar  of  incense  signified  the  office  of  the  priest,  whose 
duty  it  was  to  bring  the  people  to  God :  and  this  was  signified 
also  by  the  rod:  because  on  that  altar  the  sweet-smelling 
incense  was  burnt,  signifying  the  holiness  of  the  people 
acceptable  to  God:  for  it  is  written  (Apoc.  viii.  3)  that  the 
smoke  of  the  sweet-smelling  spices  signifies  the  justifications 
of  the  saints  [cf.  ibid.  xix.  8).  Moreover  it  was  fitting  that 
the  dignity  of  the  priesthood  should  be  denoted,  in  the  ark, 
by  the  rod,  and,  in  the  outer  tabernacle,  by  the  altar  of 
incense :  because  the  priest  is  the  mediator  between  God  and 
the  people,  governing  the  people  by  Divine  power,  denoted 
by  the  rod;  and  offering  to  God  the  fruit  of  His  government, 
i.e.,  the  holiness  of  the  people,  on  the  altar  of  incense,  so 
to  speak. — The  table  signified  the  sustenance  of  life,  just 
as  the  manna  did:  but  the  former,  a  more  general  and  a 
coarser  kind  of  nourishment ;  the  latter,  a  sweeter  and  more 
delicate. — Again,  the  candlestick  was  fittingly  placed  on  the 
southern  side,  while  the  table  was  placed  to  the  north: 
because  the  south  is  the  right-hand  side  of  the  world,  while 
the  north  is  the  left-hand  side,  as  stated  in  De  Ccelo  et 
Mundo  ii. ;  and  wisdom,  like  other  spiritual  goods,  belongs 
to  the  right  hand,  while  temporal  nourishment  belongs  to 
the  left,  according  to  Prov.  iii.  16:  In  her  left  hand  {are) 
riches  and  glory.  And  the  priestly  power  is  midway  between 
temporal  goods  and  spiritual  wisdom ;  because  thereby  both 
spiritual  wisdom  and  temporal  goods  are  dispensed. 

Another  literal  signification  may  be  assigned.  For  the 
ark  contained  the  tables  of  the  Law,  in  order  to  prevent 
forgetfulness  of  the  Law,  wherefore  it  is  written  (Exod. 
xxiv.  12) :  /  will  give  thee  two  tables  of  stone,   and  the  Law, 


g.  I02.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  '*  184 

and  the  commandments  which  I  have  written  :  that  thou  may  est 
teach  them  to  the  children  of  Israel. — The  rod  of  Aaron  was 
placed  there  to  restrain  the  people  from  insubordination 
to  the  priesthood  of  Aaron;  wherefore  it  is  written  (Num. 
xvii.  10) :  Carry  hack  the  rod  of  Aaron  into  the  tabernacle  of 
the  testimony,  that  it  may  he  keft  there  for  a  token  of  the  re- 
bellious children  of  Israel. — The  manna  was  kept  in  the  ark 
to  remind  them  of  the  benefit  conferred  by  God  on  the 
children  of  Israel  in  the  desert  ;  wherefore  it  is  written 
(Exod.  xvi.  32) :  Fill  a  gomor  of  it,  and  let  it  be  kept  unto 
generations  to  come  hereafter,  that  they  may  know  the  bread 
wherewith  I  fed  you  in  the  wilderness. — The  candlestick  was 
set  up  to  enhance  the  beauty  of  the  temple,  for  the  magnifi- 
cence of  a  house  depends  on  its  being  well  lighted.  Now 
the  candlestick  had  seven  branches,  as  Josephus  observes 
[Antiquit.  iii.),  to  signify  the  seven  planets,  wherewith  the 
whole  world  is  illuminated.  Hence  the  candlestick  was 
placed  towards  the  south;  because  for  us  the  course  of  the 
planets  is  from  that  quarter. — The  altar  of  incense  was 
instituted  that  there  might  always  be  in  the  tabernacle  a 
sweet-smelling  smoke;  both  through  respect  for  the  taber- 
nacle, and  as  a  remedy  for  the  stenches  arising  from  the 
shedding  of  blood  and  the  slaying  of  animals.  For  men 
despise  evil-smelling  things  as  being  vile,  whereas  sweet- 
smelling  things  are  much  appreciated. — The  table  was  placed 
there  to  signify  that  the  priests  who  served  the  temple 
should  take  their  food  in  the  temple:  wherefore,  as  stated 
in  Matth.  xii.  4,  it  was  lawful  for  none  but  the  priests  to  eat 
the  twelve  loaves  which  were  put  on  the  table  in  memory 
of  the  twelve  tribes.  And  the  table  was  not  placed  in  the 
middle  directly  in  front  of  the  propitiatory,  in  order  to  ex- 
clude an  idolatrous  rite:  for  the  Gentiles,  on  the  feasts  of 
the  moon,  set  up  a  table  in  front  of  the  idol  of  the  moon, 
wherefore  it  is  written  (Jerem.  vii.  18) :  The  women  knead 
the  dough,  to  make  cakes  to  the  queen  of  heaven. 

In  the  court  outside  the  tabernacle  was  the  altar  of  holo- 
causts, on  which  sacrifices  of  those  things  which  the  people 
possessed  were  offered  to  God :  and  consequently  the  people 


i85  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  4 

who  offered  these  sacrifices  to  God  by  the  hands  of  the 
priest  could  be  present  in  the  court.  But  the  priests  alone, 
whose  function  it  was  to  offer  the  people  to  God,  could 
approach  the  inner  altar,  whereon  the  very  devotion  and 
holiness  of  the  people  was  offered  to  God.  And  this  altar 
was  put  up  outside  the  tabernacle  and  in  the  court,  to  the 
exclusion  of  idolatrous  worship:  for  the  Gentiles  placed 
altars  inside  the  temples  to  offer  up  sacrifices  thereon  to  idols. 
The  figurative  reason  for  all  these  things  may  be  taken 
from  the  relation  of  the  tabernacle  to  Christ,  Who  was  fore- 
shadowed therein.  Now  it  must  be  observed  that  to  show 
the  imperfection  of  the  figures  of  the  Law,  various  figures 
were  instituted  in  the  temple  to  betoken  Christ.  For  He 
was  foreshadowed  by  the  propitiatory,  since  He  is  a  pro- 
pitiation for  our  sins  (i  John  ii.  2). — This  propitiatory  was 
fittingly  carried  by  cherubim,  since  of  Him  it  is  written 
(Heb.  i.  6) :  Let  all  the  angels  of  God  adore  Him. — He  is  also 
signified  by  the  ark:  because  just  as  the  ark  was  made  of 
setim-wood,  so  was  Christ's  body  composed  of  most  pure 
members.  Moreover  it  was  gilded:  for  Christ  was  full  of 
wisdom  and  charity,  which  are  betokened  by  gold.  And 
in  the  ark  was  a  golden  pot,  i.e..  His  holy  soul,  having 
manna,  i.e.,  all  the  fulness  of  the  Godhead  (Coloss.  ii.  9).  Also 
there  was  a  rod  in  the  ark,  i.e.,  His  priestly  power:  for  He 
was  made  a  .  .  .  priest  for  ever  (Heb.  vi.  20) .  And  therein 
were  the  tables  of  the  Testament,  to  denote  that  Christ 
Himself  is  a  lawgiver. — ^ Again,  Christ  was  signified  by  the 
candlestick,  for  He  said  Himself  (John  viii.  12) :  /  am  the 
Light  of  the  world ;  while  the  seven  lamps  denoted  the 
seven  gifts  of  the  Holy  Ghost.  He  is  also  betokened  in 
the  table,  because  He  is  our  spritual  food,  according  to 
John  vi.  41,  51 :  /  am  the  living  bread  :  and  the  twelve  loaves 
signified  the  twelve  apostles,  or  their  teaching. — Or  again, 
the  candlestick  and  table  may  signify  the  Church's  teaching, 
and  faith,  which  also  enlightens  and  refreshes. — Again, 
Christ  is  signified  by  the  two  altars  of  holocausts  and  in- 
cense. Because  all  works  of  virtue  must  be  offered  by  us 
to  God  through  Him;  both  those  whereby  we  afflict  the 


Q.  102.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  ''  186 

body,  which  are  offered,  as  it  were,  on  the  altar  of  holo- 
causts; and  those  which,  with  greater  perfection  of  mind, 
are  offered  to  God  in  Christ,  by  the  spiritual  desires  of  the 
perfect,  on  the  altar  of  incense,  as  it  were,  according  to 
Heb.  xiii.  15:  By  Him  therefore  let  us  offer  the  sacrifice  of 
praise  always  to  God. 

Reply  Ob]'.  7.  The  Lord  commanded  an  altar  to  be  made 
for  the  offering  of  sacrifices  and  gifts,  in  honour  of  God,  and 
for  the  upkeep  of  the  ministers  who  served  the  tabernacle. 
Now  concerning  the  construction  of  the  altar  the  Lord 
issued  a  twofold  precept.  One  was  at  the  beginning  of  the 
Law  (Exod.  xx.  24,  seq.)  when  the  Lord  commanded  them  to 
make  an  altar  of  earth,  or  at  least  not  of  hewn  stones  ;  and 
again,  not  to  make  the  altar  high,  so  as  to  make  it  neces- 
sary to  go  up  to  it  by  steps.  This  was  in  detestation  of 
idolatrous  worship:  for  the  Gentiles  made  their  altars 
ornate  and  high,  thinking  that  there  was  something  holy 
and  divine  in  such  things.  For  this  reason,  too,  the  Lord 
commanded  (Deut.  xvi.  21) :  Thou  shall  plant  no  grove,  nor 
any  tree  near  the  altar  of  the  Lord  thy  God  :  since  idolaters 
were  wont  to  offer  sacrifices  beneath  trees,  on  account  of 
the  pleasantness  and  shade  afforded  by  them. — There  was 
also  a  figurative  reason  for  these  precepts.  Because  we 
must  confess  that  in  Christ,  Who  is  our  altar,  there  is  the 
true  nature  of  flesh,  as  regards  His  humanity — and  this  is 
to  make  an  altar  of  earth;  and  again,  in  regard  to  His  God- 
head, we  must  confess  His  equality  with  the  Father, — and 
this  is  not  to  go  up  to  the  altar  by  steps.  Moreover  we 
should  not  couple  the  doctrine  of  Christ  to  that  of  the 
Gentiles,  which  provokes  men  to  lewdness. 

But  when  once  the  tabernacle  had  been  constructed  to 
the  honour  of  God,  there  was  no  longer  reason  to  fear  these 
occasions  of  idolatry.  Wherefore  the  Lord  commanded  the 
altar  of  holocausts  to  be  made  of  brass,  and  to  be  con- 
spicuous to  all  the  people;  and  the  altar  of  incense,  which 
was  visible  to  none  but  the  priests.  Nor  was  brass  so 
precious  as  to  give  the  people  an  occasion  for  idolatry. 

Since,  however,  the  reason  for  the  precept.   Thou  shall 


i87  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  4 

not  go  lip  by  steps  linto  My  altar  (Exod.  xx.  26)  is    stated 
to  have  been  lest  thy  nakedness  he  discovered,  it  should  be 
observed  that  this  too  was  instituted  with  the  purpose  of 
preventing  idolatry,  for  in  the  feasts  of  Priapus  the  Gentiles 
uncovered  their  nakedness  before  the  people.     But  later 
on  the  priests  were  prescribed  the  use  of  loin-cloths  for  the 
sake  of  decency:   so   that  without   any  danger   the   altar 
could  be  placed  so  high  that  the  priests  when  offering  sacri- 
fices would  go  up  by  steps  of  wood,  not  fixed  but  moveable. 
Reply  Ohj.  8.  The  body  of  the  tabernacle  consisted  of 
boards  placed  on  end,  and  covered  on  the  inside  with  cur- 
tains of  four  different  colours,  viz.,  twisted  linen,  violet, 
purple,  and  scarlet  twice  dyed.     These  curtains,  however, 
covered  the  sides  only  of   the  tabernacle  ;  and  the  roof  of 
the  tabernacle  was  covered  with  violet-coloured  skins;  and 
over  this  there  was  another  covering  of  rams'  skins  dyed  red; 
and  over  this  there  was  a  third  curtain  made  of  goats'  hair, 
which  covered  not  only  the  roof  of  the  tabernacle,  but  also 
reached  to  the  ground  and  covered  the  boards  of  the  taber- 
nacle on  the  outside.    The  literal  reason  of  these  coverings 
taken  altogether  was  the  adornment  and  protection  of  the 
tabernacle,  that  it  might  be  an  object  of  respect.     Taken 
singly,  according  to  some,  the  curtains  denoted  the  starry 
heaven,  which  is  adorned  with  various   stars;  the  curtain 
(of  goats'  skin)   signified  the  waters  which  are  above  the 
firmament;    the    skins    dyed    red    denoted    the    empyrean 
heaven,  where  the  angels  are;  the  violet  skins,  the  heaven 
of  the  Blessed  Trinity. 

The  figurative  meaning  of  these  things  is  that  the  boards 
of  which  the  tabernacle  was  constructed  signify  the 
faithful  of  Christ,  who  compose  the  Church.  The  boards 
were  covered  on  the  inner  side  by  curtains  of  four  colours: 
because  the  faithful  are  inwardly  adorned  with  the  four 
virtues:  for  the  twisted  linen,  as  the  gloss  observes,  signifies 
the  flesh  refulgent  with  purity  ;  violet  signifies  the  mind  de- 
sirous of  heavenly  things  ;  purple  denotes  the  flesh  subject  to 
passions  ;  the  twice  dyed  scarlet  betokens  the  mind  in  the 
midst  of  the  passions  enlightened  by  th:  love  of  God  and  our 


Q.  I02.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  188 

neighbour.  The  coverings  of  the  building  designate  prelates 
and  doctors,  who  ought  to  be  conspicuous  for  their  heavenly 
manner  of  life,  signified  by  the  violet  coloured  skins:  and 
who  should  also  be  ready  to  suffer  martyrdom,  denoted  by 
the  skins  dyed  red;  and  austere  of  life  and  patient  in  ad- 
versity, betokened  by  the  curtains  of  goats'  hair,  which  were 
exposed  to  wind  and  rain,  as  the  gloss  observes. 

Reply  Ohj.  9.  The  literal  reason  for  the  sanctification  of 
the  tabernacle  and  vessels  was  that  they  might  be  treated 
with  greater  reverence,  being  deputed,  as  it  were,  to  the 
divine  worship  by  this  consecration.  —  The  figurative 
reason  is  that  this  sanctification  signified  the  sanctification 
of  the  living  tabernacle,  i.e.,  the  faithful  of  whom  the 
Church  of  Christ  is  composed. 

Reply  Ohj.  10.  Under  the  Old  Law  there  were  seven  tem- 
poral solemnities,  and  one  continual  solemnity,  as  may  be 
gathered  from  Num.  xxviii.,  xxix.  There  was  a  continual 
feast,  since  the  lamb  was  sacrificed  every  day,  morning  and 
evening:  and  this  continual  feast  of  an  abiding  sacrifice 
signified  the  perpetuity  of  Divine  bliss.  Of  the  temporal 
feasts  the  first  was  that  which  was  repeated  every  week. 
This  was  the  solemnity  of  the  Sabbath,  celebrated  in  memory 
of  the  work  of  the  creation  of  the  universe. — Another 
solemnity,  viz.,  the  New  Moon,  Was  repeated  every  month, 
and  was  observed  in  memory  of  the  work  of  the  Divine 
government.  For  the  things  of  this  lower  world  owe  their 
variety  chiefly  to  the  movement  of  the  moon;  wherefore 
this  feast  was  kept  at  the  new  moon:  and  not  at  the  full 
moon,  to  avoid  the  worship  of  idolaters  who  used  to 
offer  sacrifices  to  the  moon  at  that  particular  time. — And 
these  two  blessings  are  bestowed  in  common  on  the  whole 
human  race ;   and  hence  they  were  repeated  more  frequently. 

The  other  five  feasts  were  celebrated  once  a  year:  and 
they  commemorated  the  benefits  which  had  been  conferred 
especially  on  that  people.  For  there  was  the  feast  of  the 
Passover  in  the  first  month  to  commemorate  the  blessing  of 
being  delivered  out  of  Egypt. — The  feast  of  Pentecost  was 
celebrated  fifty  days  later,  to  recall  the  blessing  of  the  giving 


i8g  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  4 

of  the  Law. — The  other  three  feasts  were  kept  in  the  seventh 
month,  nearly  the  whole  of  which  was  solemnized  by  them, 
just  as  the  seventh  day.  For  on  the  first  of  the  seventh 
month  was  the  feast  of  Trumpets,  in  memory  of  the  delivery 
of  Isaac,  when  Abraham  found  the  ram  caught  by  its  horns, 
which  they  represented  by  the  horns  which  they  blew. — 
The  feast  of  Trumpets  was  a  kind  of  invitation  whereby 
they  prepared  themselves  to  keep  the  following  feast  which 
was  kept  on  the  tenth  day.  This  was  the  feast  of  Ex- 
piation, in  memory  of  the  blessing  whereby,  at  the  prayer 
of  Moses,  God  forgave  the  people's  sin  of  worshipping  the 
calf.  After  this  was  the  feast  of  Scenopegia  or  of  the  Taber- 
nacles (i.e.,  tents),  which  was  kept  for  seven  days,  to  com- 
memorate the  blessing  of  being  protected  and  led  by  God 
through  the  desert,  where  they  lived  in  tents.  Hence 
during  this  feast  they  had  to  take  the  fruits  of  the  fairest  tree, 
i.e.,  the  citron,  and  trees  of  dense  foliage,"^  i.e.,  the  myrtle, 
which  is  fragrant,  and  branches  of  palm-trees,  and  willows 
of  the  brook,  which  retain  their  greenness  a  long  time ;  and 
these  are  to  be  found  in  the  Land  of  promise ;  to  signify  that 
God  had  brought  them  through  the  arid  land  of  the  wilder- 
ness to  a  land  of  delights. — On  the  eighth  day  another  feast 
was  observed,  of  Assembly  and  Congregation,  on  which  the 
people  collected  the  expenses  necessary  for  the  divine  wor- 
ship :  and  it  signified  the  uniting  of  the  people  and  the  peace 
granted  to  them  in  the  Land  of  promise. 

The  figurative  reason  for  these  feasts  was  that  the  con- 
tinual sacrifice  of  the  lamb  foreshadowed  the  perpetuity 
of  Christ,  Who  is  the  Lamb  of  God,  according  to  Heb.  xiii.  8 : 
Jesus  Christ  yesterday  and  to-day,  and  the  same  for  ever. — 
The  Sabbath  signified  the  spiritual  rest  bestowed  by  Christ, 
as  stated  in  Heb.  iv.  The  Neomenia,  which  is  the  beginning 
of  the  new  moon,  signified  the  enlightening  of  the  primitive 
Church  by  Christ's  preaching  and  miracles. — The  feast  of 
Pentecost  signified  the  Descent  of  the  Holy  Ghost  on  the 
apostles. — The  feast  of  Trumpets  signified  the  preaching  of 
the  apostles. — The  feast  of  Expiation  signified  the  cleansing 
*  Douay  and  A.  V.  and  R.V.  read :  Boughs  of  thick  trees. 


Q.  102.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  190 

of  the  Christian  people  from  sins:  and  the  feast  of  Taber- 
nacles signified  their  pilgrimage  in  this  world,  wherein  they 
walk  by  advancing  in  virtue. — The  feast  of  Assembly  or 
Congregation  foreshadowed  the  assembly  of  the  faithful  in 
the  kingdom  of  heaven :  wherefore  this  feast  is  described  as 
most  holy  (Levit.  xxiii.  36).  These  three  feasts  followed 
immediately  on  one  another,  because  those  who  expiate 
their  vices  should  advance  in  virtue,  until  they  come  to  see 
God,  as  stated  in  Ps.  Ixxxiii.  8. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  there  can  be  any  suitable  cause  for  the 
sacraments  of  the  old  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  can  be  no  suitable  cause 
for  the  sacraments  of  the  Old  Law.  Because  those  things 
that  are  done  for  the  purpose  of  divine  worship  should  not 
be  like  the  observances  of  idolaters:  since  it  is  written 
(Deut.  xii.  31) :  Thou  shall  not  do  in  like  manner  to  the  Lord 
thy  God  :  for  they  have  done  to  their  gods  all  the  abominations 
which  the  Lord  abhorreth.  Now  worshippers  of  idols  used  to 
knive  themselves  to  the  shedding  of  blood:  for  it  is  related 
(3  Kings  xviii.  28)  that  they  cut  themselves  after  their  manner 
with  knives  and  lancets,  till  they  were  all  covered  with  blood. 
For  this  reason  the  Lord  commanded  (Deut.  xiv.  i) :  You 
shall  not  cut  yourselves  nor  make  any  baldness  for  the  dead. 
Therefore  it  was  unfitting  for  circumcision  to  be  prescribed 
by  the  Law  (Levit.  xii.  3). 

Obj.  2.  Further,  those  things  which  are  done  for  the 
worship  of  God  should  be  marked  with  decorum  and  gravity; 
according  to  Ps.  xxxiv.  18:  /  will  praise  Thee  in  a  grave 
(Douay, — strong)  people.  But  it  seems  to  savour  of  levity 
for  a  man  to  eat  with  haste.  Therefore  it  was  unfittingly 
commanded  (Exod.  xii.  11)  that  they  should  eat  the  Paschal 
lamb  in  haste.  Other  things  too  relative  to  the  eating 
of  the  lamb  were  prescribed,  which  seem  altogether  un- 
reasonable. 


igi  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  5 

Obj.   3.  Further,   the  sacraments  of  the  Old   Law  were 
figures  of  the  sacraments  of  the  New  Law.     Now  the  Paschal 
lamb  signified  the  sacrament  of  the  luicharist,  according  to 
I  Cor.  V.  7:  Christ  our  Pasch  is  sacrificed.    Therefore  there 
should  also  have  been  some  sacraments  in  the  Old  Law 
to  foreshadow  the  other  sacraments  of  the  New  Law,  such  as 
Confirmation,  ExtremeUnction,  and  Matrimony,  and  so  forth. 
Obj.  4.  Further,  purification  can  scarcely  be  done  except 
by  removing  something  impure.     But  as  far  as  God  is  con- 
cerned, no  bodily  thing  is  reputed  impure,  because  all  bodies 
are  God's  creatures;  and  every  creature  of  God  is  good,  and 
nothing  to  be  rejected  that  is  received  with  thanksgiving  (i  Tim. 
iv.  4).     It  was  therefore  unfitting  for  them  to  be  purified 
after  contact  with  a  corpse,  or  any  similar  corporeal  infection. 
Obj.  5.  Further,  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  xxxiv.  4) :  What  can 
he  made  clean  by  the  unclean  ?     But  the  ashes  of   the  red 
heifer   [cf.   Heb.   ix.    13)   which  was  burnt,   were  unclean, 
since  they  made  a  man  unclean:  for  it  is  stated   (Num. 
xix.  7  seq.)  that  the  priest  who  immolated  her  was  rendered 
unclean  until  the  evening  ;  likewise  he  that  burnt  her ;  and 
he  that  gathered  up  her  ashes.     Therefore  it  was  unfittingly 
prescribed  there  that  the  unclean  should  be  purified  by 
being  sprinkled  with  those  cinders. 

Obj.  6.  Further,  sins  are  not  something  corporeal  that 
can  be  carried  from  one  place  to  another:  nor  can  man  be 
cleansed  from  sin  by  means  of  something  unclean.  It  was 
therefore  unfitting  for  the  purpose  of  expiating  the  sins  of 
the  people  that  the  priest  should  confess  the  sins  of  the 
children  of  Israel  on  one  of  the  buck-goats,  that  it  might 
carry  them  away  into  the  wilderness:  while  they  were 
rendered  unclean  by  the  other,  which  they  used  for  the 
purpose  of  purification,  by  burning  it  together  with  the  calf 
outside  the  camp;  so  that  they  had  to  wash  their  clothes 
and  their  bodies  with  water  (Levit.  xvi.). 

Obj.  7.  Further,  what  is  already  cleansed  should  not  be 
cleansed  again.  It  was  therefore  unfitting  to  apply  a  second 
purification  to  a  man  cleansed  from  leprosy,  or  to  a  house; 
as  laid  down  in  Levit.  xiv. 


Q.  I02.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  192 

Ohj.  8.  Further,  spiritual  uncleanness  cannot  be  cleansed 
by  material  water  or  by  shaving  the  hair.  Therefore 
it  seems  unreasonable  that  the  Lord  ordered  (Exod.  xxx.  18 
seq.)  the  making  of  a  brazen  laver  with  its  foot,  that  the 
priests  might  wash  their  hands  and  feet  before  entering  the 
temple;  and  that  He  commanded  (Num.  viii.  7)  the  Levites 
to  be  sprinkled  with  the  water  of  purification,  and  to  shave 
all  the  hairs  of  their  flesh. 

Ohj.  9.  Further,  that  which  is  greater  cannot  be  cleansed 
by  that  which  is  less  Therefore  it  was  unfitting  that,  in 
the  Law,  the  higher  and  lower  priests,  as  stated  in  Levit.  viii. 
(c/.  Exod.  xxix.),  and  the  Levites,  according  to  Num.  viii., 
should  be  consecrated  with  any  bodily  anointing,  bodily 
sacrifices,  and  bodily  oblations. 

Ohj.  10.  Further,  as  stated  in  i  Kings  xvi.  7,  Man  seeth 
those  things  that  appear,  hut  the  Lord  heholdeth  the  heart. 
But  those  things  that  appear  outwardly  in  man  are  the 
disposition  of  his  body  and  his  clothes.  Therefore  it  was 
unfitting  for  certain  special  garments  to  be  appointed  to 
the  higher  and  lower  priests,  as  related  in  Exod.  xxviii. 
{cf.  Levit.  viii.  7,  seq.).  It  seems,  moreover,  unreasonable 
that  anyone  should  be  debarred  from  the  priesthood  on 
account  of  defects  in  the  body,  as  stated  in  Levit.  xxi.  17, 
seq. :  Whosoever  of  thy  seed  throughout  their  families,  hath 
a  hlemish,  he  shall  not  offer  bread  to  his  God.  .  .  .  if  he  he  blind, 
if  he  he  lame,  etc.  It  seems,  therefore,  that  the  sacraments 
of  the  Old  Law  were  unreasonable. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  (Levit.  xx.  S):  I  am  the  Lord 
that  sanctify  you.  But  nothing  unreasonable  is  done  by 
God,  for  it  is  written  (Ps.  ciii.  24) :  Thou  hast  made  all  things 
in  wisdom.  Therefore  there  was  nothing  without  a  reason- 
able cause  in  the  sacraments  of  the  Old  Law,  which  were 
ordained  to  the  sanctification  of  man. 

7  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CI.,  A.  4),  the  sacra- 
ments are,  properly  speaking,  things  applied  to  the  wor- 
shippers of  God  for  their  consecration  so  as,  in  some  way, 
to  depute  them  to  the  worship  of  God.  Now  the  worship 
of  God  belonged  in  a  general  way  to  the  whole  people ;  but 


193  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  5. 

in  a  special  way,  it  belonged  to  the  priests  and  Levites,  who 
were  the  ministers  of  divine  worship.  Consequently,  in 
these  sacraments  of  the  Old  Law,  certain  things  concerned 
the  whole  people  in  general;  while  others  belonged  to  the 
ministers. 

In  regard  to  both,  three  things  were  necessary.  The  first 
was  to  be  established  in  the  state  of  worshipping  God:  and 
this  institution  was  brought  about, — for  all  in  general,  by^ 
circumcision,  without  which  no  one  was  admitted  to  any 
of  the  legal  observances, — and  for  the  priests,  by  their 
consecration.  The  second  thing  required  was  the  use  of 
those  things  that  pertain  to  divine  worship.  And  thus, 
as  to  the  people,  there  was  the  partaking  of  the  paschal 
banquet,  to  which  no  uncircumcised  man  was  admitted, 
as  is  clear  from  Exod.  xii.  43,  seq. :  and,  as  to  the  priests,  the 
offering  of  the  victims,  and  the  eating  of  the  loaves  of 
proposition  and  of  other  things  that  were  allotted  to  the  use 
of  the  priests. — The  third  thing  required  was  the  removal 
of  all  impediments  to  divine  worship,  viz.,  of  uncleannesses. 
And  then,  as  to  the  people,  certain  purifications  were  insti- 
tuted for  the  removal  of  certain  external  uncleannesses; 
and  also  expiations  from  sins;  while,  as  to  the  priests  and 
Levites,  the  washing  of  hands  and  feet  and  the  shaving  of 
the  hair  were  instituted. 

And  all  these  things  had  reasonable  causes,  both  literal, 
in  so  far  as  they  were  ordained  to  the  worship  of  God  for  the 
time  being,  and  figurative,  in  so  far  as  they  were  ordained  to 
foreshadow  Christ :  as  we  shall  see  by  taking  them  one  by  one. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  chief  literal  reason  for  circumcision 
was  in  order  that  man  might  profess  his  belief  in  one  God. 
And  because  Abraham  was  the  first  to  sever  himself  from 
the  infidels,  by  going  out  from  his  house  and  kindred  for 
this  reason  he  was  the  first  to  receive  circumcision.  This 
reason  is  set  forth  by  the  Apostle  (Rom.  iv.  9,  seq.)  thus: 
He  received  the  sign  of  circumcision,  a  seal  of  the  justice  of 
the  faith  which  he  had,  being  uncircumcised  ;  because,  to  wit, 
we  are  told  that  unto  Abraham  faith  was  reputed  to  justice, 
for  the  reason  that  against  hope  he  believed  in  hope,  i.e., 

"•3  13 


g.  102.  Art.  5     THE  ''  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  194 

against  the  hope  that  is  of  nature  he  believed  in  the  hope 
that  is  of  grace,  that  he  might  he  made  the  father  of  many 
nations,  when  he  was  an  old  man,  and  his  wife  an  old  and 
barren  woman.  And  in  order  that  this  declaration,  and  imita- 
tion of  Abraham's  faith,  might  be  fixed  firmly  in  the  hearts 
of  the  Jews,  they  received  in  their  flesh  such  a  sign  as  they 
could  not  forget,  wherefore  it  is  written  (Gen.  xvii.  13) : 
My  covenant  shall  he  in  your  flesh  for  a  perpetual  covenant. 
This  was  done  on  the  eighth  day,  because  until  then  a  child 
is  very  tender,  and  so  might  be  seriously  injured;  and  is 
considered  as  something  not  yet  consolidated:  wherefore 
neither  are  animals  offered  before  the  eighth  day.  And  it  was 
not  delayed  after  that  time,  lest  some  might  refuse  the  sign 
of  circumcision  on  account  of  the  pain:  and  also  lest  the 
parents,  whose  love  for  their  children  increases  as  they  be- 
come used  to  their  presence  and  as  they  grow  older,  should 
withdraw  their  children  from  circumcision. — A  second 
reason  may  have  been  the  weakening  of  concupiscence  in 
that  member. — A  third  motive  may  have  been  to  revile  the 
worship  of  Venus  and  Priapus,  which  gave  honour  to  that 
part  of  the  body. — The  Lord's  prohibition  extended  only 
to  the  cutting  of  oneself  in  honour  of  idols:  and  such  was 
not  the  circumcision  of  which  we  have  been  speaking. 

The  figurative  reason  for  circumcision  was  that  it  fore- 
shadowed the  removal  of  corruption,  which  was  to  be 
brought  about  by  Christ,  and  will  be  perfectly  fulfilled  in 
the  eighth  age,  which  is  the  age  of  those  who  rise  from  the 
dead.  And  since  all  corruption  of  guilt  and  punishment 
comes  to  us  through  our  carnal  origin,  from  the  sin  of  our 
first  parent,  therefore  circumcision  was  applied  to  the 
generative  member.  Hence  the  Apostle  says  (Coloss.  ii. 
11) :  You  are  circumcised  in  Christ  with  circumcision  not  made 
hy  hand  in  despoiling  of  the  hody  of  the  flesh,  hut  in  the  circum- 
cision of  Our  Lord  Jesus  Christ. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  literal  reason  of  the  paschal  banquet 
was  to  commemorate  the  blessing  of  being  led  by  God  out 
of  Egypt.  Hence  by  celebrating  this  banquet  they  declared 
that  they  belonged  to  that  people  which  God  had  taken  to 


195  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  3 

Himself  out  of  Egypt.  For  when  they  were  delivered  from 
Egypt,  they  were  commanded  to  sprinkle  the  lamb's  blood  on 
the  transoms  of  their  house  doors,  as  though  declaring  that 
they  were  averse  to  the  rites  of  the  Egyptians  who  worshipped 
the  ram.  Wherefore  they  were  delivered  by  the  sprinkling  or 
rubbing  of  the  blood  of  the  lamb  on  the  door-posts,  from  the 
danger  of  extermination  which  threatened  the  Egyptians. 

Now  two  things  are  to  be  observed  in  their  departure  from 
Egypt:  namely,  their  haste  in  going,  for  the  Egyptians 
pressed  them  to  go  forth  speedily,  as  related  in  Exod.  xii.  33 ; 
and  there  was  the  danger  that  anyone  who  did  not  hasten 
to  go  with  the  crowd  might  be  slain  by  the  Egyptians. 
Their  haste  was  shown  in  two  ways.  First  by  what  they 
ate.  For  they  Were  commanded  to  eat  unleavened  bread, 
as  a  sign  that  it  could  not  he  leavened,  the  Egyptians  pressing 
them  to  depart ;  and  to  eat  roast  meat,  for  this  took  less  time 
to  prepare ;  and  that  they  should  not  break  a  bone  thereof, 
because  in  their  haste  there  was  no  time  to  break  bones. 
Secondly,  as  to  the  manner  of  eating.  For  it  is  written: 
You  shall  gird  your  reins,  and  you  shall  have  shoes  on  your 
feet,  holding  staves  in  your  hands,  and  you  shall  eat  in  haste  : 
which  clearly  designates  men  at  the  point  of  starting  on 
a  journey.  To  this  also  is  to  be  referred  the  command: 
In  one  house  shall  it  he  eaten,  neither  shall  you  carry  forth 
of  the  flesh  thereof  out  of  the  house  :  because,  to  wit,  on  ac- 
count of  their  haste,  they  could  not  send  any  gifts  of  it. 

The  stress  they  suffered  while  in  Egypt  was  denoted  by 
the  wild  lettuces.  The  figurative  reason  is  evident,  because 
the  sacrifice  of  the  paschal  lamb  signified  the  sacrifice  of 
Christ  according  to  i  Cor.  v.  7 :  Christ  our  pasch  is  sacrificed. 
The  blood  of  the  lamb,  which  ensured  deliverance  from  the 
destroyer,  by  being  sprinkled  on  the  transoms,  signified 
faith  in  Christ's  Passion,  in  the  hearts  and  on  the  lips  of  the 
faithful,  by  which  same  Passion  we  are  delivered  from  sin 
and  death,  according  to  i  Pet.  i.  18:  You  were  .  .  .  redeemed 
.  .  .  with  the  precious  hlood  .  .  .  of  a  lamh  unspotted.  The 
partaking  of  its  flesh  signified  the  eating  of  Christ's  body  in 
the  Sacrament ;  and  the  flesh  was  roasted  at  the  fire  to 


Q.  102.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  196 

signify  Christ's  Passion  or  charity.  And  it  was  eaten  with 
unleavened  bread  to  signify  the  blameless  life  of  the  faithful 
who  partake  of  Christ's  body,  according  to  i  Cor.  v.  8:  Let 
us  feast  .  .  .  with  the  unleavened  bread  of  sincerity  and  truth. 
The  wild  lettuces  were  added  to  denote  repentance  for  sins, 
which  is  required  of  those  who  receive  the  body  of  Christ. 
Their  loins  were  girt  in  sign  of  chastity :  and  the  shoes  of 
their  feet  are  the  examples  of  our  dead  ancestors.  The 
staves  they  were  to  hold  in  their  hands  denoted  pastoral 
authority:  and  it  was  commanded  that  the  paschal  lamb 
should  be  eaten  in  one  house,  i.e.,  in  a  catholic  church,  and 
not  in  the  conventicles  of  heretics. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Some  of  the  sacraments  of  the  New  Law 
had  corresponding  figurative  sacraments  in  the  Old  Law. 
For  Baptism,  which  is  the  sacrament  of  Faith,  corresponds 
to  circumcision.  Hence  it  is  written  (Col.  ii.  11,  12) :  You 
are  circumcised  .  .  .  in  the  circumcision  of  Our  Lord  Jesus 
Christ ;  buried  with  Him  in  Baptism.  In  the  New  Law  the 
sacrament  of  the  Eucharist  corresponds  to  the  banquet  of 
the  paschal  lamb.  The  sacrament  of  Penance  in  the  New 
Law  corresponds  to  all  the  purifications  of  the  Old  Law. 
The  sacrament  of  Orders  corresponds  to  the  consecration  of 
the  pontiff  and  of  the  priests.  To  the  sacrament  of  Con- 
firmation, which  is  the  sacrament  of  the  fulness  of  grace, 
there  would  be  no  corresponding  sacrament  of  the  Old  Law, 
because  the  time  of  fulness  had  not  yet  come,  since  the  Law 
brought  no  man  (Vulg., — nothing)  to  perfection  (Heb.  vii.  19). 
The  same  applies  to  the  sacrament  of  Extreme  Unction, 
which  is  an  immediate  preparation  for  entrance  into  glory, 
to  which  the  way  was  not  yet  opened  out  in  the  Old  Law, 
since  the  price  had  not  yet  been  paid.  Matrimony  did 
indeed  exist  under  the  Old  Law,  as  a  function  of  nature,  but 
not  as  the  sacrament  of  the  union  of  Christ  with  the  Church, 
for  that  union  was  not  as  yet  brought  about.  Hence  under 
the  Old  Law  it  was  allowable  to  give  a  bill  of  divorce,  which 
is  contrary  to  the  nature  of  a  sacrament. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  As  already  stated,  the  purifications  of  the 
Old  Law  were  ordained  for  the  removal  of  impediments  to 


197  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS       Q.  T02.  Art.  5 

the  divine  worship:  which  worship  is  twofold;  viz.,  spiritual, 
consisting  in  devotion  of  the  mind  to  God;  and  corporal, 
consisting  in  sacrifices,  oblations,  and  so  forth.  Now  men 
are  hindered  in  the  spiritual  worship  by  sins,  whereb^^  men 
were  said  to  be  polluted,  for  instance,  by  idolatry,  murder, 
adultery,  or  incest.  From  such  pollutions  men  were  purified 
by  certain  sacrifices,  offered  either  for  the  whole  community 
in  general,  or  also  for  the  sins  of  individuals;  not  that  those 
carnal  sacrifices  had  of  themselves  the  power  of  expiating 
sin;  but  that  they  signified  that  expiation  of  sins  which  was 
to  be  effected  by  Christ,  and  of  Which  those  of  old  became 
partakers  by  protesting  their  faith  in  the  Redeemer,  while 
taking  part  in  the  figurative  sacrifices. 

The  impediments  to  external  worship  consisted  in  certain 
bodily  uncleannesses ;  which  were  considered  in  the  first  place 
as  existing  in  man,  and  consequently  in  other  animals  also, 
and  in  man's  clothes,  dwelling-place,  and  vessels.  In  man  him- 
self uncleanness  was  considered  as  arising  partly  from  himself 
and  partly  from  contact  with  unclean  things.  Anything 
proceeding  from  man  was  reputed  unclean  that  was  already 
subject  to  corruption,  or  exposed  thereto :  and  consequently 
since  death  is  a  kind  of  corruption,  the  human  corpse  was 
considered  unclean.  In  like  manner,  since  leprosy  arises 
from  corruption  of  the  humours,  which  break  out  externally 
and  infect  other  persons,  therefore  were  lepers  also  con- 
sidered unclean;  and,  again,  women  suffering  from  a  flow 
of  blood,  whether  from  weakness,  or  from  nature  (either  at 
the  monthly  course  or  at  the  time  of  conception) ;  and,  for 
the  same  reason,  men  were  reputed  unclean  if  they  suffered 
from  a  flow  of  seed,  whether  due  to  weakness,  to  nocturnal 
pollution,  or  to  sexual  intercourse.  Because  every  humour 
issuing  from  man  in  the  aforesaid  ways  involves  some 
unclean  infection.  Again,  man  contracted  uncleanness  by 
touching  any  unclean  thing  whatever. 

Now  there  was  both  a  literal  and  a  figurative  reason  for 
these  uncleannesses.  The  literal  reason  was  taken  from  the 
reverence  due  to  those  things  that  belong  to  the  divine 
worship :  »botli  because  men  are  not  wont,  when  unclean,  to 


Q.  I02.  Art.  5     THR  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  198 

touch  precious  things :  and  in  order  that  by  rarely  approach- 
ing sacred  things  they  might  have  greater  respect  for  them. 
For  since  man  could  seldom  avoid  all  the  aforesaid  unclean- 
nesses,  the  result  was  that  men  could  seldom  approach  to 
touch  things  belonging  to  the  worship  of  God,  so  that  when 
they  did  approach,  they  did  so  with  greater  reverence  and 
humility.  Moreover,  in  some  of  these  the  literal  reason  was 
that  men  should  not  be  kept  away  from  worshipping  God 
through  fear  of  coming  in  contact  with  lepers  and  others 
similarly  afflicted  with  loathsome  and  contagious  diseases. 
In  others,  again,  the  reason  was  to  avoid  idolatrous  worship; 
because  in  their  sacrificial  rites  the  Gentiles  sometimes  em- 
ployed human  blood  and  seed.  All  these  bodily  unclean- 
nesses  were  purified  either  by  the  mere  sprinkling  of  water, 
or,  in  the  case  of  those  which  were  more  grievous,  by  some 
sacrifice  of  expiation  for  the  sin  which  was  the  occasion  of 
the  uncleanness  in  question. 

The  figurative  reason  for  these  uncleannesses  was  that 
they  were  figures  of  various  sins.  For  the  uncleanness  of 
any  corpse  signifies  the  uncleanness  of  sin,  which  is  the 
death  of  the  soul.  The  uncleanness  of  leprosy  betokened 
the  uncleanness  of  heretical  doctrine:  both  because  heretical 
doctrine  is  contagious  just  as  leprosy  is,  and  because  no 
doctrine  is  so  false  as  not  to  have  some  truth  mingled  with  error, 
as  Augustine  says  (QucBst.  Evang.  iii.),  just  as  on  the  sur- 
face of  a  leprous  body  one  may  distinguish  the  healthy 
parts  from  those  that  are  infected.  The  uncleanness  of  a 
woman  suffering  from  a  flow  of  blood  denotes  the  unclean- 
ness of  idolatry,  on  account  of  the  blood  which  is  offered 
up.  The  uncleanness  of  the  man  who  has  suffered  seminal 
loss  signifies  the  uncleanness  of  empty  words,  for  the  seed 
is  the  word  of  God.  The  uncleanness  of  sexual  intercourse 
and  of  the  woman  in  child-birth  signifies  the  uncleanness  of 
original  sin.  The  uncleanness  of  the  woman  in  her  periods 
signifies  the  uncleanness  of  a  mind  that  is  sensualized  by 
pleasure.  Speaking  generally,  the  uncleanness  contracted 
by  touching  an  unclean  thing  denotes  the  uncleanness 
arising  from  consent  in  another's  sin,  according  to  2  Cor. 


199  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  5 

vi.  17:  Go  out  from  among  them,  and  he  ye  separate  .  .  .  and 
touch  not  the  unclean  thing. 

Moreover,  this  uncleanness  arising  from  the  touch  was 
contracted  even  by  inanimate  objects;  for  whatever  was 
touched  in  any  way  by  an  unclean  man,  became  itself 
unclean.  Wherein  the  Law  attenuated  the  superstition  of 
the  Gentiles,  who  held  that  uncleanness  was  contracted  not 
only  by  touch,  but  also  by  speech  or  looks,  as  Rabbi  Moses 
states  [Doctr.  Perplex,  iii.)  of  a  woman  in  her  periods.  The 
mystical  sense  of  this  was  that  to  God  the  wicked  and  his 
wickedness  are  hateful  alike  (Wis.  xiv.  9). 

There  was  also  an  uncleanness  of  inanimate  things  con- 
sidered in  themselves,  such  as  the  uncleanness  of  leprosy  in 
a  house  or  in  clothes.  For  just  as  leprosy  occurs  in  men 
through  a  corrupt  humour  causing  putrefaction  and  cor- 
ruption in  the  flesh;  so,  too,  through  some  corruption  and 
excess  of  humidity  or  dryness,  there  arises  sometimes  a  kind 
of  corruption  in  the  stones  with  which  a  house  is  built,  or 
in  clothes.  Hence  the  Law  called  this  corruption  by  the 
name  of  leprosy,  whereby  a  house  or  a  garment  was  deemed 
to  be  unclean:  both  because  al]  corruption  savoured  of 
uncleanness,  as  stated  above,  and  because  the  Gentiles  wor- 
shipped their  household  gods  as  a  preservative  against  this 
corruption.  Hence  the  Law  prescribed  such  houses,  where 
this  kind  of  corruption  was  of  a  lasting  nature,  to  be  de- 
stroyed; and  such  garments  to  be  burnt,  in  order  to  avoid 
all  occasion  of  idolatry.  There  was  also  an  uncleanness  of 
vessels,  of  which  it  is  written  (Num.  xix.  15) :  The  vessel  that 
hath  no  cover,  and  binding  over  it,  shall  he  unclean.  The 
cause  of  this  uncleanness  was  that  anything  unclean  might 
easily  drop  into  such  vessels,  so  as  to  render  them  unclean. 
Moreover,  this  command  aimed  at  the  prevention  of 
idolatry.  For  idolaters  believed  that  if  mice,  lizards,  or 
the  like,  which  they  used  to  sacrifice  to  the  idols,  fell  into 
the  vessels  or  into  the  water,  these  became  more  pleasing  to 
the  gods.  Even  now  some  women  let  down  uncovered  vessels 
in  honour  of  the  nocturnal  deities  whom  they  call  JancB. 

The   figurative   reason   of    these   uncleannesses    is    that 


Q.  102.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  200 

the  leprosy  of  a  house  signified  the  uncleanness  of  the 
assembly  of  heretics;  the  leprosy  of  a  linen  garment  sig- 
nified an  evil  life  arising  from  bitterness  of  mind ;  the  leprosy 
of  a  woollen  garment  denoted  the  wickedness  of  flatterers; 
leprosy  in  the  warp  signified  the  vices  of  the  soul;  leprosy 
on  the  woof  denoted  sins  of  the  flesh,  for  as  the  warp  is  in 
the  woof,  so  is  the  soul  in  the  body.  The  vessel  that  has 
neither  cover  nor  binding,  betokens  a  man  who  lacks  the 
veil  of  taciturnity,  and  who  is  unrestrained  by  any  severity 
of  discipline. 

Reply  Ohj.  5.  As  stated  above  [ad  4),  there  was  a  twofold 
uncleanness  in  the  Law;  one  by  way  of  corruption  in  the 
mind  or  in  the  body;  and  this  was  the  graver  uncleanness ; 
the  other  was  by  mere  contact  with  an  unclean  thing,  and 
this  was  less  grave,  and  was  more  easily  expiated.  Because 
the  former  uncleanness  was  expiated  by  sacrifices  for  sins, 
since  all  corruption  is  due  to  sin,  and  signifies  sin:  whereas 
the  latter  uncleanness  was  expiated  by  the  mere  sprinkling 
of  a  certain  water,  of  which  water  we  read  in  Num.  xix.  For 
there  God  commanded  them  to  take  a  red  cow  in  memory 
of  the  sin  they  had  committed  in  worshipping  a  calf.  And 
a  cow  is  mentioned  rather  than  a  calf,  because  it  was  thus 
that  the  Lord  was  wont  to  designate  the  synagogue,  accord- 
ing to  Osee  iv.  16:  Israel  hath  gone  astray  like  a  wanton 
heifer  :  and  this  was,  perhaps,  because  they  worshipped 
heifers  after  the  custom  of  Egypt,  according  to  Osee  x.  5 : 
{They)  have  worshipped  the  kine  of  Bethaven.  And  in 
detestation  of  the  sin  of  idolatry  it  was  sacrificed  out- 
side the  camp;  in  fact,  whenever  sacrifice  was  offered 
up  in  expiation  of  the  multitude  of  sins,  it  was  all  burnt 
outside  the  camp.  Moreover,  in  order  to  show  that  this 
sacrifice  cleansed  the  people  from  all  their  sins,  the  priest 
dipped  his  finger  in  her  blood,  and  sprinkled  it  over  against 
the  door  of  the  tabernacle  seven- times  ;  for  the  number  seven 
signifies  universality.  Further,  the  very  sprinkling  of  blood 
pertained  to  the  detestation  of  idolatry,  in  which  the  blood 
that  was  offered  up  was  not  poured  out,  but  was  collected 
together,  and  men  gathered  round  it  to  eat  in  honour  of 


201  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  5 

the  idols.     Likewise  it  was  burnt  by  fire,  either  because 
God  appeared  to  Moses  in  a  lire,  and  the  Law  was  given 
from  the  midst  of  fire;  or  to  denote  that  idolatry,  together 
with  all  that  was  connected  therewith,  was  to  be  extirpated 
altogether;  just  as  the  cow  was  burnt  with  her  skin  and  her 
flesh,  her  blood  and  dung  being  delivered  to  the  flames.     To 
this  burning  were  added  cedar-wood,  and  hyssop,  and  scarlet 
twice  dyed,  to  signify  that  just  as  cedar- wood  is  not  liable  to 
putrefaction,  and  scarlet  twice  dyed  does  not  easily  lose  its 
colour,  and  hyssop  retains  its  odour  after  it  has  been  dried ; 
so  also  was  this  sacrifice  for  the  preservation  of  the  whole 
people,  and  for  their  good  behaviour  and  devotion.     Hence 
it  is  said  of  the  ashes  of  the  cow:  That  they  may  be  reserved 
for  the  multitude  of  the  children  of  Israel.     Or,  according  to 
Josephus  [Antiq.  iii.),  the  four  elements  are  indicated  here: 
for  cedar-wood  was  added  to  the  fire,  to  signify  the  earth,  on 
account  of  its  earthiness;  hyssop,   to  signify  the  air,   on 
account  of  its  smell ;  scarlet  twice  dyed,  to  signify  water,  for 
the  same  reason  as  purple,  on  account  of  the  dyes  which 
are  taken  out  of  the  water: — thus  denoting  the  fact  that 
this  sacrifice  was  offered  to  the  Creator  of  the  four  elements. 
And  since  this  sacrifice  was  offered  for  the  sin  of  idolatry, 
both  he  that  burned  her,  and  he  that  gathered  up  the  ashes,  and 
he  that  sprinkled  the  water  in  which  the  ashes  were  placed, 
were  deemed  unclean  in  detestation  of  that  sin,  in  order  to 
show  that  whatever  was  in  any  way  connected  with  idolatry 
should  be  cast  aside  as  being  unclean.     From  this  unclean- 
ness  they  were  purified  by  the  mere  washing  of  their  clothes ; 
nor  did  they  need  to  be  sprinkled  with  the  water  on  account 
of  this  kind  of  uncleanness,  because  otherwise  the  process 
would  have  been  unending,  since  he  that  sprinkled  the  water 
became  unclean,  so  that  if  he  were  to  sprinkle  himself  he 
would  remain  unclean;  and  if  another  were  to  sprinkle  him, 
that  one  would  have  become  unclean,  and  in  like  manner, 
whoever  might  sprinkle  him,  and  so  on  indefinitely. 

The  figurative  reason  of  this  sacrifice  was  that  the  red 
cow  signified  Christ  in  respect  of  his  assumed  weakness, 
denoted  by  the  female  sex;  while  the  colour  of  the  cow 


Q.  I02.  Art.  5    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  202 

designated  the  blood  of  His  Passion.     And  the  red  cow  was 
of  full  age,  because  all  Christ's  works  are  perfect,  in  which 
there  was  no  blemish  ;  and  which  had  not  carried  the  yoke, 
because  Christ  was  innocent,  nor  did  He  carry  the  yoke  of 
sin.     It  was  commanded  to  be  taken  to  Moses,  because  they 
blamed  Him  for  transgressing  the  law  of  Moses  by  breaking 
the  Sabbath.     And  it  was  commanded  to  be  delivered  to 
Eleazar  the  priest,  because  Christ  was  delivered  into    the 
hands  of  the  priests  to  be  slain.     It  was  immolated  without 
the  camp,  because  Christ  suffered  outside  the  gate  (Heb.  xiii.  12). 
And  the  priest  dipped  his  finger  in  her  blood,  because  the  mys- 
tery of  Christ's  Passion  should  be  considered  and  imitated. 
It  was  sprinkled  over  against  .  .  .  the  tabernacle,  which 
denotes  the  synagogue,  to  signify  either  the  condemnation 
of  the  unbelieving  Jews,  or  the  purification  of  believers;  and 
this  seven  times,  in  token  either  of  the  seven  gifts  of  the 
Holy  Ghost,  or  of  the  seven  days  wherein  all  time  is  com- 
prised.    Again,  all  things  that  pertain  to  the  Incarnation  of 
Christ  should  be  burnt  with  fire,  i.e.,  they  should  be  under- 
stood spiritually;  for  the  skin  and  flesh  signified  Christ's 
outward  works;  the  blood  denoted  the  subtle  inward  force 
which  quickened  His  external  deeds:  the  dung  betokened 
His  weariness,  His  thirst,  and  all  suchlike  things  pertaining 
to  His  weakness.     Three  things  were  added,  viz.,   cedar- 
wood,  which  denotes  the  height  of  hope  or  contemplation; 
hyssop,  in  token  of  humility  or  faith;  scarlet  twice  dyed, 
which  denotes  twofold  charity;  for  it  is  by  these  three  that 
we   should  cling  to   Christ   suffering.     The   ashes   of  this 
burning  were  gathered  by  a  man  that  is  clean,  because  the 
relics  of  the  Passion  came  into  the  possession  of  the  Gentiles, 
who  were  not  guilty  of  Christ's  death.     The  ashes  were  put 
into  water  for  the  purpose  of  expiation,  because  Baptism 
receives  from  Christ's  Passion  the  power  of  washing  away 
sins.     The  priest  who  immolated  and  burned  the  cow,  and 
he  who  burned,  and  he  who  gathered  together  the  ashes, 
were  unclean,  as  also  he  that  sprinkled  the  water:  either 
because  the  Jews  became  unclean  through  putting  Christ  to 
death,  whereby  our  sins  are  expiated;  and  this,  until  the 


203  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  5 

evening,  i.e.,  until  the  end  of  the  world,  when  the  remnants 
of  Israel  will  be  converted;  or  else  because  they  who  handle 
sacred  things  with  a  view  to  the  cleansing  of  others  contract 
certain  uncleannesses,  as  Gregory  says  [Pastor,  ii.) ;  and  this 
until  the  evening,  i.e.,  until  the  end  of  this  life. 

Reply  Obj.   6.  As  stated  above   [ad  5),   an   uncleanness 
which  was  caused  by  corruption  either  of  mind  or  of  body 
was  expiated  by  sin-offerings.     Now  special  sacrifices  were 
wont  to  be  offered  for  the  sins  of  individuals:  but  since 
some  were  neglectful  about  expiating  such  sins  and  unclean- 
nesses; or,  through  ignorance,  failed  to  offer  this  expiation; 
it  was  laid  down  that  once  a  year,  on  the  tenth  day  of  the 
seventh  month,  a  sacrifice  of  expiation  should  be  offered 
for  the  whole  people.     And  because,  as  the  Apostle  says 
(Heb.  vii.  28),  the  Law  maketh  men  priests,  who  have   in- 
firmity, it  behoved  the  priest  first  of  all  to  offer  a  calf  for 
his  own  sins,  in  memory  of  Aaron's  sin  in  fashioning  the 
molten  calf;  and  besides,  to  offer  a  ram  for  a  holocaust, 
which  signified  that  the  priestly  sovereignty  denoted  by  the 
ram,  who  is  the  head  of  the  flock,  was  to  be  ordained  to  the 
glory  of  God. — Then  he  offered  two  he-goats  for  the  people : 
one  of  which  was  offered  in  expiation  of  the  sins  of  the 
multitude.     For  the  he-goat  is  an  evil-smelling  animal;  and 
from  its  skin  clothes  are  made  having  a  pungent  odour;  to 
signify  the  stench,  uncleanness  and  the  sting  of  sin.     After 
this   he-goat   had   been   immolated,  its   blood  was   taken, 
together  with  the  blood  of  the  calf,  into  the  Holy  of  Holies, 
and  the  entire  sanctuary  was  sprinkled  with  it;  to  signify 
that  the  tabernacle  was  cleansed  from  the  uncleannesses  of 
the  children  of  Israel.     But  the  corpses  of  the  he-goat  and 
calf  which  had  been  offered  up  for  sin  had  to  be  burnt,  to 
denote  the  destruction  of  sins.     They  were  not,  however, 
burnt  on  the  altar:  since  none  but  holocausts  were  burnt 
thereon;  but  it  was  prescribed  that  they  should  be  burnt 
without  the  camp,  in  detestation  of  sin:  for  this  was  done 
whenever  sacrifice  was  offered  for  a  grievous  sin,  or  for  the 
multitude  of  sins.     The  other  goat  was  let  loose  into  the 
wilderness:  not  indeed  to  offer  it  to  the  demons,  whom  the 


Q.  T02.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  204 

Gentiles  worshipped  in  desert  places,  because  it  was  unlaw- 
ful to  offer  aught  to  them;  but  in  order  to  point  out  the 
effect  of  the  sacrifice  which  had  been  offered  up.  Hence 
the  priest  put  his  hand  on  its  head,  while  confessing  the 
sins  of  the  children  of  Israel:  as  though  that  goat  were  to 
carry  them  away  into  the  wilderness,  where  it  would  be 
devoured  by  wild  beasts,  because  it  bore  the  punishment 
of  the  people's  sins.  And  it  was  said  to  bear  the  sins  of  the 
people,  either  because  the  forgiveness  of  the  people's  sins 
was  signified  by  its  being  let  loose,  or  because  on  its  head 
written  lists  of  sins  were  fastened. 

The  figurative  reason  of  these  things  was  that  Christ  was 
foreshadowed  both  by  the  calf,  on  account  of  His  power; 
and  by  the  ram,  because  He  is  the  Head  of  the  faithful ;  and 
by  the  he-goat,  on  account  of  the  likeness  of  sinful  flesh 
(Rom.  viii.  3).  Moreover,  Christ  was  sacrificed  for  the  sins 
of  both  priests  and  people:  since  both  those  of  high  and 
those  of  low  degree  are  cleansed  from  sin  by  His  Passion. 
The  blood  of  the  calf  and  of  the  goat  was  brought  into  the 
Holies  by  the  priest,  because  the  entrance  to  the  kingdom 
of  heaven  was  opened  to  us  by  the  blood  of  Christ's  Passion. 
Their  bodies  were  burnt  without  the  camp,  because  Christ 
suffered  without  the  gate,  as  the  Apostle  declares  (Heb. 
xiii.  12).  The  scape-goat  may  denote  either  Christ's  God- 
head, Which  went  away  into  solitude  when  the  Man  Christ 
suffered,  not  by  going  to  another  place,  but  by  restraining 
His  power:  or  it' may  signify  the  base  concupiscence  which 
we  ought  to  cast  away  from  ourselves,  while  we  offer  up  to 
Our  Lord  acts  of  virtue. 

With  regard  to  the  uncleanness  contracted  by  those  who 
burnt  these  sacrifices,  the  reason  is  the  same  as  that  which 
we  assigned  [ad  5)  to  the  sacrifice  of  the  red  heifer. 

Rej)ly  Obj.  7.  The  legal  rite  did  not  cleanse  the  leper  of 
his  deformity,  but  declared  him  to  be  cleansed.  This  is 
shown  by  the  words  of  Lev.  xiv.  3,  seq.,  where  it  is  said  that 
the  priest,  when  he  shall  find  that  the  leprosy  is  cleansed, 
shall  command  him  that  is  to  be  purified  :  consequently,  the 
leper  was  already  healed:  but  he  was  said  to  be  purified  in 


205  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS         Q.  102.  Art.  5 

so  far  as  the  verdict  of  the  priest  restored  him  to  the  society 
of  men  and  to  the  worship  of  God.  It  happened  sometimes, 
however,  that  bodily  leprosy  was  miraculously  cured  by  the 
legal  rite,  when  the  priest  erred  in  his  judgment. 

Now  this  purilication  of  a  leper  was  twofold:  for,  in  the 
first  place,  he  was  declared  to  be  clean;  and,  secondly,  he 
was  restored,  as  clean,  to  the  society  of  men  and  to  the 
worship  of  God,  to  wit,  after  seven  days.  At  the  first 
purification  the  leper  who  sought  to  be  cleansed  offered  for 
himself  two  living  sparrows,  .  .  .  cedar-wood,  and  scarlet, 
and  hyssop,  in  such  wise  that  a  sparrow  and  the  hyssop 
should  be  tied  to  the  cedar-wood  with  a  scarlet  thread,  so 
that  the  cedar- wood  was  like  the  handle  of  an  aspersory: 
while  the  hyssop  and  sparrow  were  that  part  of  the  aspersory 
which  was  dipped  into  the  blood  of  the  other  sparrow  which 
was  immolated  .  .  .  over  living  waters.  These  things  he 
offered  as  an  antidote  to  the  four  defects  of  leprosy:  for 
cedar- wood,  which  is  not  subject  to  putrefaction,  was  offered 
against  the  putrefaction;  hyssop,  which  is  a  sweet-smelling 
herb,  was  offered  up  against  the  stench ;  a  living  sparrow  was 
offered  up  against  numbness;  and  scarlet,  which  has  a  vivid 
colour,  was  offered  up  against  the  repulsive  colour  of  leprosy. 
The  living  sparrow  was  let  loose  to  fly  away  into  the  plain, 
because  the  leper  was  restored  to  his  former  liberty. 

On  the  eighth  day  he  was  admitted  to  divine  worship, 
and  was  restored  to  the  society  of  men;  but  only  after 
having  shaved  all  the  hair  of  his  body,  and  washed  his 
clothes,  because  leprosy  rots  the  hair,  infects  the  clothes, 
and  gives  them  an  evil  smell.  Afterwards  a  sacrifice  was 
offered  for  his  sin,  since  leprosy  was  frequently  a  result  of 
sin:  and  some  of  the  blood  of  the  sacrifice  was  put  on  the 
tip  of  the  ear  of  the  man  that  was  to  be  cleansed,  and  on  the 
thumb  of  his  right  hand,  and  the  great  toe  of  his  right  foot ; 
because  it  is  in  these  parts  that  leprosy  is  first  diagnosed 
and  felt.  In  this  rite,  moreover,  three  liquids  were  em- 
ployed: viz.,  blood,  against  the  corruption  of  the  blood;  oil, 
to  denote  the  healing  of  the  disease;  and  living  waters,  to 
wash  away  the  filth. 


g.  I02  Art.  5      THE  "  SUMMA  TH1^:0L0GICA  "  206 

The  figurative  reason  was  that  the  Divine  and  human 
natures  in  Christ  were  denoted  by  the  two  sparrows,  one  of 
which,  in  likeness  of  His  human  nature,  was  offered  up  in  an 
earthen  vessel  over  living  waters,  because  the  waters  of 
Baptism  are  sanctified  by  Christ's  Passion.  The  other 
sparrow,  in  token  of  His  impassible  Godhead,  remained 
living,  because  the  Godhead  cannot  die :  hence  it  flew  away, 
for  the  Godhead  could  not  be  encompassed  by  the  Passion. 
Now  this  living  sparrow,  together  with  the  cedar-wood  and 
scarlet  or  cochineal,  and  hyssop,  i.e.,  faith,  hope,  and 
charity,  as  stated  above  (ad  5),  was  put  into  the  water  for 
the  purpose  of  sprinkling,  because  we  are  baptized  in  the 
faith  of  the  God-Man.  By  the  waters  of  Baptism  or  of  his 
tears  man  washes  his  clothes,  i.e.,  his  works,  and  all  his 
hair,  i.e.,  his  thoughts.  The  tip  of  the  right  ear  of  the  man 
to  be  cleansed  is  moistened  with  some  of  the  blood  and  oil, 
in  order  to  strengthen  his  hearing  against  harmful  words; 
and  the  thumb  and  toe  of  his  right  hand  and  foot  are 
moistened  that  his  deeds  may  be  holy.  Other  matters 
pertaining  to  this  purification,  or  to  that  also  of  any 
other  uncleannesses,  call  for  no  special  remark,  beyond 
what  applies  to  other  sacrifices,  whether  for  sins  or  for 
trespasses. 

Reply  Ohjs.  8  and  9.  Just  as  the  people  were  initiated  by 
circumcision  to  the  divine  worship,  so  were  the  ministers 
by  some  special  purification  or  consecration:  wherefore 
they  are  commanded  to  be  separated  from  other  men,  as 
being  specially  deputed,  rather  than  others,  to  the  ministry 
of  the  divine  worship.  And  all  that  was  done  touching 
them  in  their  consecration  or  institution,  was  with  a  view 
to  show  that  they  were  in  possession  of  a  prerogative  of 
purity,  power,  and  dignity.  Hence  three  things  were  done 
in  the  institution  of  ministers:  for  first,  they  were  purified; 
secondly,  they  were  adorned*  and  consecrated ;  thirdly,  they 
were  employed  in  the  ministry.  All  in  general  used  to  be 
purified  by  washing  in  water,  and  by  certain  sacrifices;  but 

*  Ornabantur.     Some  editions  have  ordinahantur , — were  ordained  : 
the  former  reading  is  a  reference  to  Lev.  viii.  7-9. 


207  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  5 

the  Levites  in  particular  shaved  aU  the  hair  of  their  bodies, 
as  stated  in  Lev.  viii.  {cf.  Num.  viii.). 

With  regard  to  the  high-priests  and  priests  the  consecra- 
tion was  performed  as  follows.  First,  when  they  had  been 
washed,  they  were  clothed  with  certain  special  garments 
in  designation  of  their  dignity.  In  particular,  the  high- 
priest  was  anointed  on  the  head  with  the  oil  of  unction :  to 
denote  that  the  power  of  consecration  was  poured  forth  by 
him  on  to  others,  just  as  oil  flows  from  the  head  on  to  the 
lower  parts  of  the  body;  according  to  Ps.  cxxxii.  2:  Like 
the  precious  ointment  on  the  head  that  ran  down  upon  the 
heard,  the  heard  of  Aaron.  But  the  Levites  received  no  other 
consecration  besides  being  offered  to  the  Lord  by  the  children 
of  Israel  through  the  hands  of  the  high-priest,  who  prayed 
for  them.  The  lesser  priests  were  consecrated  on  the  hands 
only,  which  were  to  be  employed  in  the  sacrifices.  The  tip 
of  their  right  ear  and  the  thumb  of  their  right  hand,  and  the 
great  toe  of  their  right  foot  were  tinged  with  the  blood  of 
the  sacrificial  animal,  to  denote  that  they  should  be  obedient 
to  God's  law  in  offering  the  sacrifices  (this  is  denoted  by 
touching  their  right  ear) ;  and  that  they  should  be  careful 
and  ready  in  performing  the  sacrifices  (this  is  signified  by 
the  moistening  of  the  right  foot  and  hand) .  They  themselves 
and  their  garments  were  sprinkled  with  the  blood  of  the 
animal  that  had  been  sacrificed,  in  memory  of  the  blood  of 
the  lamb  by  which  they  had  been  delivered  in  Egypt.  At 
their  consecration  the  following  sacrifices  were  offered:  a 
calf,  for  sin,  in  memory  of  Aaron's  sin  in  fashioning  the 
molten  calf ;  a  ram,  for  a  holocaust,  in  memory  of  the  sacri- 
fice of  Abraham,  whose  obedience  it  behoved  the  high-priest 
to  imitate;  again,  a  ram  of  consecration,  which  was  as  a 
peace-offering,  in  memory  of  the  delivery  from  Egypt 
through  the  blood  of  the  lamb;  and  a  basket  of  bread,  in 
memory  of  the  manna  vouchsafed  to  the  people. 

In  reference  to  their  being  destined  to  the  ministry,  the 
fat  of  the  ram,  one  roll  of  bread,  and  the  right  shoulder  were 
placed  on  their  hands,  to  show  that  they  received  the 
power  of  offering  these  things  to  the  Lord :  while  the  Levites 


Q.  I02.  Art.  5      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  208 

were  initiated  to  the  ministry  by  being  brought  into  the 
tabernacle  of  the  covenant,  as  being  destined  to  the  ministry 
touching  the  vessels  of  the  sanctuary. 

The  figurative  reason  of  these  things  was  that  those  who  are 
to  be  consecrated  to  the  spiritual  ministry  of  Christ,  should 
be  first  of  all  purified  by  the  waters  of  Baptism,  and  by  the 
waters  of  tears,  in  their  faith  in  Christ's  Passion,  which  is  a 
sacrifice  both  of  expiation  and  of  purification.  They  have 
also  to  shave  all  the  hair  of  their  body,  i.e.,  all  evil  thoughts. 
They  should,  moreover,  be  decked  with  virtues,  and  be  conse- 
crated with  the  oil  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  and  with  the  sprinkling 
of  Christ's  blood.  And  thus  they  should  be  intent  on  the 
fulfilment  of  their  spiritual  ministry. 

Reply  Ohj.  10.  As  already  stated  (A.  4),  the  purpose  of 
the  Law  was  to  induce  men  to  have  reverence  for  the  divine 
worship:  and  this  in  two  ways; — ^first,  by  excluding  from 
the  worship  of  God  whatever  might  be  an  object  of  con- 
tempt ;  secondly,  by  introducing  into  the  divine  worship  all 
that  seemed  to  savour  of  reverence.  x\nd,  indeed,  if  this 
was  observed  in  regard  to  the  tabernacle  and  its  vessels, 
and  in  the  animals  to  be  sacrificed,  much  more  was  it  to  be 
observed  in  the  very  ministers.  Wherefore,  in  order  to 
obviate  contempt  for  the  ministers,  it  was  prescribed  that 
they  should  have  no  bodily  stain  or  defect:  since  men  so 
deformed  are  wont  to  be  despised  by  others.  For  the  same 
reason  it  was  also  commanded  that  the  choice  of  those  who 
were  to  be  destined  to  the  service  of  God  was  not  to  be  made 
in  a  broadcast  manner  from  any  family,  but  according  to 
their  descent  from  one  particular  stock,  thus  giving  them 
distinction  and  nobility. 

In  order  that  they  might  be  revered,  special  ornate  vest- 
ments were  appointed  for  their  use,  and  a  special  form  of 
consecration.  This  indeed  is  the  general  reason  of  ornate 
garments.  But  the  high-priest  in  particular  had  eight  vest- 
ments. First,  he  had  a  linen  tunic. — Secondly,  he  had  a 
purple  tunic;  round  the  bottom  of  which  were  placed  little 
bells  [and  as  it  were)  pomegranates  of  violet,  and  purple,  and 
scarlet    twice    dyed. — Thirdly,    he    had    the    ephod,    which 


209  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS    Q.  102.  Art.  5 

covered  his  shoulders  and  his  breast  down  to  the  girdle ;  and 
it  was  made  of  gold,  and  violet  and  purple,  and  scarlet  twice 
dyed  and  twisted  linen:  and  on  his  shoulders  he  bore  two 
onyx  stones,  on  which  were  graven  the  names  of  the  children 
of  Israel. — Fourthly,  he  had  the  rational,  made  of  the  same 
material;  it  was  square  in  shape,  and  was  worn  on  the  breast, 
and  was  fastened  to  the  ephod.  On  this  rational  there  were 
twelve  precious  stones  set  in  four  rows,  on  which  also  were 
graven  the  names  of  the  children  of  Israel,  in  token  that  the 
priest  bore  the  burden  of  the  whole  people,  since  he  bore 
their  names  on  his  shoulders;  and  that  it  was  his  duty  ever 
to  think  of  their  welfare,  since  he  wore  them  on  his  breast, 
bearing  them  in  his  heart,  so  to  speak.  And  the  Lord  com- 
manded the  Doctrine  and  Truth  to  be  put  in  the  rational: 
for  certain  matters  regarding  moral  and  dogmatic  truth 
were  written  on  it.  The  Jews  indeed  pretend  that  on 
the  rational  was  placed  a  stone  which  changed  colour  ac- 
cording to  the  various  things  which  were  about  to  happen 
to  the  children  of  Israel:  and  this  they  call  the  Truth  and 
Doctrine. — Fifthly,  he  wore  a  belt  or  girdle  made  of  the  four 
colours  mentioned  above. — Sixthly,  there  was  the  tiara  or 
mitre  which  was  made  of  linen. — Seventhly,  there  was  the 
golden  plate  which  hung  over  his  forehead;  on  it  was  in- 
scribed the  Lord's  name. — Eighthly,  there  were  the  linen 
breeches  to  cover  the  flesh  of  their  nakedness,  when  they  went 
up  to  the  sanctuary  or  altar. — Of  these  eight  vestments  the 
lesser  priests  had  four,  viz.,  the  linen  tunic  and  breeches, 
the  belt  and  the  tiara. 

According  to  some,  the  literal  reason  for  these  vestments 
was  that  they  denoted  the  disposition  of  the  terrestrial 
globe ;  as  though  the  high- priest  confessed  himself  to  be  the 
minister  of  the  Creator  of  the  world,  wherefore  it  is  written 
(Wis.  xviii.  24) :  In  the  robe  of  Aaron  was  the  whole  world 
described.  For  the  linen  breeches  signified  the  earth  out 
of  which  the  flax  grows.  The  surrounding  belt  signified  the 
ocean  which  surrounds  the  earth.  The  violet  tunic  denoted 
the  air  by  its  colour:  its  little  bells  betoken  the  thunder; 
the  pomegranates,  the  lightning.     The  ephod,  by  its  many 

n.3  14 


Q.  102.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  210 

colours,  signified  the  starry  heaven;  the  two  onyx  stones 
denoted  the  two  hemispheres,  or  the  sun  and  moon.  The 
twelve  precious  stones  on  the  breast  are  the  twelve  signs 
of  the  zodiac:  and  they  are  said  to  have  been  placed  on  the 
rational,  because  in  heaven  are  the  types  [rationes)  of  earthly 
things,  according  to  Job  xxxviii.  33:  Dost  thou  know  the 
order  of  heaven,  and  canst  thou  set  down  the  reason  [rationem) 
thereof  on  the  earth  ?  The  turban  or  tiara  signified  the 
empyrean:  the  golden  plate  was  a  token  of  God,  the  governor 
of  the  universe. 

The  figurative  reason  is  evident.  Because  bodily  stains 
or  defects  wherefrom  the  priests  had  to  be  immune,  signify 
the  various  vices  and  sins  from  which  they  should  be 
free.  Thus  it  is  forbidden  that  he  should  be  blind,  i.e., 
he  ought  not  to  be  ignorant:  he  must  not  be  lame,  i.e., 
vacillating  and  uncertain  of  purpose :  that  he  must  not  have 
a  little,  or  a  great,  or  a  crooked  nose,  i.e.,  that  he  should 
not,  from  lack  of  discretion,  exceed  in  one  direction  or  in 
another,  or  even  exercise  some  base  occupation:  for  the 
nose  signifies  discretion,  because  it  discerns  odours.  It  is 
forbidden  that  he  should  have  a  broken  foot  or  hand,  i.e.,  he 
should  not  lose  the  power  of  doing  good  works  or  of  ad- 
vancing in  virtue.  He  is  rejected,  too,  if  he  have  a  swelling 
either  in  front  or  behind  (Vulg., — if  he  he  crookhacked) :  by 
which  is  signified  too  much  love  of  earthly  things : — if  he  be 
blear-eyed,  i.e.,  if  his  mind  is  darkened  by  carnal  affections: 
for  running  of  the  eyes  is  caused  by  a  flow  of  matter.  He  is 
also  rejected  if  he  have  a  pearl  in  his  eye,  i.e.,  if  he  pre- 
sumes in  his  own  estimation  that  he  is  clothed  in  the  white 
robe  of  righteousness.  Again,  he  is  rejected  if  he  have  a 
continued  scab,  i.e.,  lustfulness  of  the  flesh:  also,  if  he  have 
a  dry  scurf,  which  covers  the  body  without  giving  pain,  and 
is  a  blemish  on  the  comeliness  of  the  members ;  which  denotes 
avarice.  Lastly,  he  is  rejected  if  he  have  a  rupture  or  hernia ; 
through  baseness  rending  his  heart,  though  it  appear  not  in 
his  deeds. 

The  vestments  denote  the  virtues  of   God's  ministers. 
Now  there  are  four  things  that  are  necessary  to  all  His 


211  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  5 

ministers,  viz.,  chastity  denoted  by  the  breeches;  a  pure  life, 
signified  by  the  linen  tunic;  the  moderation  of  discretion, 
betokened  by  the  girdle;  and  rectitude  of  purpose,  denoted 
by  the  mitre  covering  the  head. — But  the  high- priests  needed 
four  other  things  in  addition  to  these.  First,  a  continual 
recollection  of  God  in  their  thoughts ;  and  this  was  signifii  d 
by  the  golden  plate  worn  over  the  forehead,  with  the  name 
of  God  engraved  thereon.  Secondly,  they  had  to  bear  with 
the  shortcomings  of  the  people:  this  was  denoted  by  the 
ephod  which  they  bore  on  their  shoulders.  Thirdly,  they 
had  to  carry  the  people  in  their  mind  and  heart  by  the 
solicitude  of  charity,  in  token  of  which  they  wore  the 
rational.  Fourthly,  they  had  to  lead  a  godly  life  by  perform- 
ing works  of  perfection ;  and  this  was  signified  by  the  violet 
tunic.  Hence  little  golden  bells  were  fixed  to  the  bottom  of 
the  violet  tunic,  which  bells  signified  the  teaching  of  divine 
things  united  in  the  high-priest  to  his  godly  mode  of  life. 
In  addition  to  these  were  the  pomegranates,  signifying  unity 
of  faith  and  concord  in  good  morals:  because  his  doctrine 
should  hold  together  in  such  a  way  that  it  should  not  rend 
asunder  the  unity  of  faith  and  peace. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  there  was  any  reasonable  cause  for  the 
ceremonial  observances  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  was  no  reasonable  cause 
for  the  ceremonial  observances.  Because,  as  the  Apostle 
says  (i  Tim.  iv.  4),  every  creature  of  God  is  good,  and  nothing 
to  he  rejected  that  is  received  with  thanksgiving.  It  was  there- 
fore unfitting  that  they  should  be  forbidden  to  eat  certain 
foods,  as  being  unclean  according  to  Lev.  xi.  {cf.  Deut.  xiv.). 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  just  as  animals  are  given  to  man  for  food, 
so  also  are  herbs:  wherefore  it  is  written  (Gen.  ix.  3) :  As  the 
green  herbs  have  I  delivered  all  flesh  to  you.  But  the  Law  did 
not  distinguish  any  herbs  from  the  rest  as  being  unclean, 
although  some  are  most  harmful,  for  instance,  those  that 


Q.  T02.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  212 

are  poisonous.  Therefore  it  seems  that  neither  should  any 
animals  have  been  prohibited  as  being  unclean. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  if  the  matter  from  which  a  thing  is  gene- 
rated be  unclean,  it  seems  that  likewise  the  thing  generated 
therefrom  is  unclean.  But  flesh  is  generated  from  blood.  Since 
therefore  all  flesh  was  not  prohibited  as  unclean,  it  seems 
that  in  like  manner  neither  should  blood  have  been  forbidden 
as  unclean;  nor  the  fat  which  is  engendered  from  blood. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Our  Lord  said  (Matth.  x.  28;  cf.  Luke 
xii.  4),  that  those  should  not  be  feared  that  kill  the  body, 
since  after  death  they  have  no  more  that  they  can  do  :  which 
would  not  be  true  if  after  death  harm  might  come  to  man 
through  anything  done  with  his  body.  Much  less  therefore 
does  it  matter  to  an  animal  already  dead  how  its  flesh 
be  cooked.  Consequently  there  seems  to  be  no  reason  in 
what  is  said,  Exod.  xxiii.  19 :  Thou  shall  not  boil  a  kid  in  the 
milk  of  its  dam. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  all  that  is  first  brought  forth  of  man  and 
beast,  as  being  most  perfect,  is  commanded  to  be  offered  to 
the  Lord  (Exod.  xiii.).  Therefore  it  is  an  unfitting  command 
that  is  set  forth  in  Lev.  xix.  23 :  when  you  shall  be  come  into 
the  land,  and  shall  have  planted  in  it  fruit  trees,  you  shall 
take  away  the  un circumcision'^  of  them,  i.e.,  the  first  crops,  and 
they  shall  be  unclean  to  you,  neither  shall  you  eat  of  them. 

Obj.  6.  Further,  clothing  is  something  extraneous  to  man's 
body.  Therefore  certain  kinds  of  garments  should  not  have 
been  forbidden  to  the  Jews:  for  instance  (Lev.  xix.  19): 
Thou  shall  not  wear  a  garment  that  is  woven  of  two  sorts  :  and 
(Deut.  xxii.  5) :  A  woman  shall  not  be  clothed  with  man's 
apparel,  neither  shall  a  man  use  woman's  apparel :  and  further 
on  (verse  11) :  Thou  shall  not  wear  a  garment  that  is  woven  of 
woollen  and  linen  together. 

Obj.  7.  Further,  to  be  mindful  of  God's  commandments 
concerns  not  the  body  but  the  heart.  Therefore  it  is  un- 
suitably prescribed  (Deut.  vi.  8,  seq.)  that  they  should  hind 
the  commandments  of  God  as  a  sign  on  their  hands;  and 
that  they  should  write  them  in  the  entry ;  and  (Num.  xv.  38, 
*  PrcBputia,  which  Douay  version  renders  ,^^5/  fruits. 


213  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  6 

scq.)  that  they  should  make  to  themselves  fringes  in  the 
corners  of  their  garments,  putting  in  them  ribands  of  blue,  that 
.  .  .  they  may  remember  .  .  .  the  commandments  of  the  Lord. 

Obj.  8.  Further,  the  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  ix.  9)  that  God 
doth  not  take  care  for  oxen,  and,  therefore,  neither  of  other 
irrational  animals.  Therefore  without  reason  is  it  com- 
manded (Deut.  xxii.  6):  If  thou  find,  as  thou  walkest  by  the 
way,  a  bird's  nest  in  a  tree  .  .  .  thou  shalt  7tot  take  the  dam 
with  her  young  ;  and  (Deut.  xxv.  4) :  Thou  shalt  not  muzzle 
the  ox  that  treadeth  out  thy  corn  ;  and  (Lev.  xix.  19) :  Thou 
shalt  not  7nake  thy  cattle  to  gender  with  beasts  of  any  other  kind. 

Obj.  9.  Further,  no  distinction  was  made  between  clean 
and  unclean  plants.  Much  less  therefore  should  any  dis- 
tinction have  been  made  about  the  cultivation  of  plants. 
Therefore  it  was  unfittingly  prescribed  (Lev.  xix.  19) :  Thou 
shalt  not  sow  thy  field  with  different  seeds  ;  and  (Deut.  xxii.  9, 
seq.)\  Thou  shalt  sow  thy  vineyard  with  divers  seeds;  and: 
Thou  shalt  not  plough  with  an  ox  and  an  ass  together. 

Obj.  10.  Further,  it  is  apparent  that  inanimate  things  arc 
most  of  all  subject  to  the  power  of  man.  Therefore  it  was 
unfitting  to  debar  man  from  taking  the  silver  and  gold  of 
which  idols  were  made,  or  anything  they  found  in  the  houses 
of  idols,  as  expressed  in  the  commandment  of  the  Law 
(Deut.  vii.  25,  seq.).  It  also  seems  an  absurd  commandment 
set  forth  in  Deut.  xxiii.  13,  that  they  should  dig  round  about 
and  .   .  .  cover  with  earth  that  which  they  were  eased  of. 

Obj.  II.  Further,  piety  is  required  especially  in  priests. 
But  it  seems  to  be  an  act  of  piety  to  assist  at  the  burial  of 
one's  friends:  wherefore  Tobias  is  commended  for  so  doing 
(Tob.  i.  20,  seqq.).  In  like  manner  it  is  sometimes  an  act  of 
piety  to  marry  a  loose  woman,  because  she  is  thereby  de- 
livered from  sin  and  infamy.  Therefore  it  seems  inconsis- 
tent for  these  things  to  be  forbidden  to  priests  (Lev.  xxi.). 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Deut.  xviii.  14) :  But  thou  art 
otherwise  instructed  by  the  Lord  thy  God  :  from  which  words 
we  may  gather  that  these  observances  were  instituted  by 
God  to  be  a  special  prerogative  of  that  people.  Therefore 
they  are  not  without  reason  or  cause. 


Q.  I02.  Art.  g     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  214 

I  answer  that,  The  Jewish  people,  as  stated  above  (A.  5), 
were  specially  chosen  for  the  worship  of  God,  and  among 
them  the  priests  themselves  were  specially  set  apart  for 
that  purpose.  And  just  as  other  things  that  are  applied  to 
the  divine  worship,  need  to  be  marked  in  some  particular 
way  so  that  they  be  worthy  of  the  worship  of  God;  so 
too  in  that  people's,  and  specially  the  priests',  mode  of 
life,  there  needed  to  be  certain  special  things  befitting  the 
divine  worship,  whether  spiritual  or  corporal.  Now  the 
worship  prescribed  by  the  Law  foreshadowed  the  mystery 
of  Christ:  so  that  whatever  they  did  was  a  figure  of  things 
pertaining  to  Christ,  according  to  i  Cor.  x.  11:  All  these 
things  happened  to  them  in  figures.  Consequently  the  reasons 
for  these  observances  may  be  taken  in  two  ways,  first  accord- 
ing to  their  fittingness  to  the  worship  of  God;  secondly, 
according  as  they  foreshadow  something  touching  the  Chris- 
tian mode  of  life. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  stated  above  (A.  5,  ad  4,  5),  the  Law 
distinguished  a  twofold  pollution  or  uncleanness;  one,  that 
of  sin,  whereby  the  soul  was  defiled;  and  another  consisting 
in  some  kind  of  corruption,  whereby  the  body  was  in  some 
way  infected.  Speaking  then  of  the  first-mentioned  un- 
cleanness, no  kind  of  food  is  unclean,  or  can  defile  a  man, 
by  reason  of  its  nature;  wherefore  we  read  (Matth.  xv.  11) : 
Not  that  which  goeth  into  the  mouth  defileth  a  man  ;  hut  what 
Cometh  out  of  the  mouth,  this  defileth  a  man :  which  words  are 
explained  (verse  17)  as  referring  to  sins.  Yet  certain  foods 
can  defile  the  soul  accidentally;  in  so  far  as  man  partakes 
of  them  against  obedience  or  a  vow,  or  from  excessive  con- 
cupiscence; or  through  their  being  an  incentive  to  lust,  for 
which  reason  some  refrain  from  wine  and  flesh-meat. 

If,  however,  we  speak  of  bodily  uncleanness,  consisting  in 
some  kind  of  corruption,  the  flesh  of  certain  animals  is  un- 
clean, either  because  like  th-e  pig  they  feed  on  unclean 
things ;  or  because  their  life  is  among  unclean  surroundings : 
thus  certain  animals,  like  moles  and  mice  and  suchlike,  live 
underground,  whence  they  contract  a  certain  unpleasant 
smell;  or  because  their  flesh,  through  being  too  moist  or  too 


215  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  6 

dry,  engenders  corrupt  humours  in  the  human  body.  Hence 
they  were  forbidden  to  eat  the  flesh  of  flat-footed  animals, 
i.e.,  animals  having  an  uncloven  hoof,  on  account  of  their 
earthiness;  and  in  like  manner  they  were  forbidden  to  eat 
the  flesh  of  animals  that  have  many  clefts  in  their  feet, 
because  such  are  very  fierce  and  their  flesh  is  very  dry,  such 
as  the  flesh  of  lions  and  the  like.  For  the  same  reason  they 
were  forbidden  to  eat  certain  birds  of  prey  the  flesh  of 
which  is  very  dry,  and  certain  water-fowl  on  account  of 
their  exceeding  humidity.  In  like  manner  certain  fish 
lacking  fins  and  scales  were  prohibited  on  account  of  their 
excessive  moisture;  such  as  eels  and  the  like.  They  were, 
however,  allowed  to  eat  ruminants  and  animals  with  a 
divided  hoof,  because  in  such  animals  the  humours  are  well 
absorbed,  and  their  nature  well  balanced:  for  neither  are 
they  too  moist,  as  is  indicated  by  the  hoof;  nor  are  they  too 
earthy,  which  is  shown  by  their  having  not  a  flat  but  a 
cloven  hoof.  Of  fishes  they  were  allowed  to  partake  of  the 
drier  kinds,  of  which  the  fins  and  scales  are  an  indication, 
because  thereby  the  moist  nature  of  the  fish  is  tempered. 
Of  birds  they  were  allowed  to  eat  the  tamer  kinds,  such  as 
hens,  partridges,  and  the  like. — Another  reason  was  detesta- 
tion of  idolatry:  because  the  Gentiles,  and  especially  the 
Egyptians,  among  whom  they  had  grown  up,  offered  up 
these  forbidden  animals  to  their  idols,  or  employed  them  for 
the  purpose  of  sorcery:  whereas  they  did  not  eat  those 
animals  which  the  Jews  were  allowed  to  eat,  but  worshipped 
them  as  gods,  or  abstained,  for  some  other  motive,  from 
eating  them,  as  stated  above  (A.  ^  ad  2).  The  third  reason 
was  to  prevent  excessive  care  about  food:  wherefore  they 
were  allowed  to  eat  those  animals  which  could  be  procured 
easily  and  promptly. 

With  regard  to  blood  and  fat,  they  were  forbidden  to 
partake  of  those  of  any  animal  whatever  without  exception. 
Blood  was  forbidden,  both  in  order  to  avoid  cruelty,  that 
they  might  abhor  the  shedding  of  human  blood,  as  stated 
above  (A  3.  ad  8) ;  and  in  order  to  shun  the  idolatrous  rite 
whereby  it  was  customary  for  men  to  collect  the  blood  and 


Q.  I02.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  216 

to  gather  together  around  it  for  a  banquet  in  honour  of  the 
idols,  to  whom  they  held  the  blood  to  be  most  acceptable. 
Hence  the  Lord  commanded  the  blood  to  be  poured  out  and 
to  be  covered  with  earth  (Lev.  xvii.  13). — For  the  same 
reason  they  were  forbidden  to  eat  animals  that  had  been 
suffocated  or  strangled:  because  the  blood  of  these  animals 
would  not  be  separated  from  the  body:  or  because  this  form 
of  death  is  very  painful  to  the  victim ;  and  the  Lord  wished 
to  withdraw  them  from  cruelty  even  in  regard  to  irrational 
animals,  so  as  to  be  less  inclined  to  be  cruel  to  other  men, 
through  being  used  to  be  kind  to  beasts.  They  were  for- 
bidden to  eat  the  fat :  both  because  idolaters  ate  it  in  honour 
of  their  gods ;  and  because  it  used  to  be  burnt  in  honour  of 
God;  and,  again,  because  blood  and  fat  are  not  nutritious, 
which  is  the  cause  assigned  by  Rabbi  Moses  [Doctr.  Per- 
plex, iii.). — The  reason  why  they  were  forbidden  to  eat  the 
sinews  is  given  in  Gen.  xxxii.  32,  where  it  is  stated  that  the 
children  of  Israel  .  .  .  eat  not  the  sinew  .  .  .  because  he  touched 
the  sinew  0/ Jacob's  thigh  and  it  shrank. 

The  figurative  reason  for  these  things  is  that  all  these 
animals  signified  certain  sins,  in  token  of  which  those 
animals  were  prohibited.  Hence  Augustine  says  [Contra 
Faustum  vi.) :  //  the  swine  and  lamb  be  called  in  question,  both 
are  clean  by  nature,  because  all  God's  creatures  are  good  :  yet 
the  lamb  is  clean,  and  the  pig  is  unclean  in  a  certain  significa- 
tion. Thus  if  you  speak  of  a  foolish,  and  of  a  wise  man,  each 
of  these  expressions  is  clean  considered  in  the  nature  of  the 
sound,  letters  and  syllables  of  which  it  is  composed  :  but  in 
signification,  the  one  is  clean,  the  other  unclean.  The  animal 
that  chews  the  cud  and  has  a  divided  hoof,  is  clean  in 
signification.  Because  division  of  the  hoof  is  a  figure  of  the 
two  Testaments:  or  of  the  Father  and  Son:  or  of  the  two 
natures  in  Christ :  of  the  distinction  of  good  and  evil.  While 
chewing  the  cud  signifies  meditation  on  the  Scriptures  and 
a  sound  understanding  thereof;  and  whoever  lacks  either 
of  these  is  spiritually  unclean. — In  like  manner  those  fish 
that  have  scales  and  fins  are  clean  in  signification.  Because 
fins  signify  the  heavenly  or  contemplative  life;  while  scales 


217  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  102.  Art.  6 

signify  a  life  of  trials,  each  of  which  is  required  for  spiritual 
cleanness. — Of  birds  certain  special  kinds  were  forbidden.    In 
the  eagle  which  flies  at  a  great  height,  pride  is  forbidden: 
in  the  griffon  which  is  hostile  to  horses  and  men,  cruelty  of 
powerful  men  is  prohibited.     The  osprey,  which  feeds  on 
very  small  birds,  signifies  those  who  oppress  the  poor.     The 
kite,  which  is  full  of  cunning,  denotes  those  who  are  fraudu- 
lent in  their  dealings.     The  vulture,  which  follows  an  army, 
expecting  to  feed  on  the  carcases  of  the  slain,  signifies  those 
who  like  others  to  die  or  to  fight  among  themselves  that 
they  may  gain  thereby.     Birds  of  the  raven  kind  signify 
those  who  are  blackened  by  their  lusts;  or  those  who  lack 
kindly  feelings,  for  the  raven  did  not  return  when  once  it 
had  been  let  loose  from  the  ark.     The  ostrich  which,  though 
a  bird,  cannot  fly,  and  is  always  on  the  ground,  signifies  those 
who  fight  for  God's  cause,  and  at  the  same  time  are  taken 
up  with  worldly  business.     The  owl,  which  sees  clearly  at 
night,  but  cannot  see  in  daytime,  denotes  those  who  are 
clever  in  temporal  affairs,   but  dull  in  spiritual  matters. 
The  gull,  which  both  flies  in  the  air  and  swims  in  the  water, 
signifies  those  who  are  partial  both  to  Circumcision  and  to 
Baptism :  or  else  it  denotes  those  who  would  fly  by  contem- 
plation, yet  dwell  in  the  waters  of  sensual  delights.     The 
hawk,  which  helps  men  to  seize  the  prey,  is  a  figure  of  those 
who  assist  the  strong  to  prey  on  the  poor.     The  screech-owl, 
which  seeks  its  food  by  night  but  hides  by  day,  signifies  the 
lustful  man  who  seeks  to  lie  hidden  in  his  deeds  of  darkness. 
The  cormorant,  so  constituted  that  it  can  stay  a  long  time 
under  water,   denotes  the  glutton  who   plunges  into   the 
waters  of  pleasure.     The  ibis  is  an  African  bird  with  a  long 
beak,  and  feeds  on  snakes;  and  perhaps  it  is  the  same  as 
the  stork :  it  signifies  the  envious  man,  who  refreshes  himself 
with  the  ills  of  others,  as  with  snakes.     The  swan  is  bright 
in  colour,  and  by  the  aid  of  its  long  neck  extracts  its  food 
from  deep  places  on  land  or  water:  it  may  denote  those 
who  seek  earthly  profit  through  an  external  brightness  of 
virtue.     The  bittern  is  a  bird  of  the  East :  it  has  a  long  beak, 
and  its  jaws  are  furnished  with  foUicules,  wherein  it  stores 


g.  I02.  Art.  6     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  218 

its  food  at  first,  after  a  time  proceeding  to  digest  it :  it  is  a 
figure  of  the  miser,  who  is  excessively  careful  in  hoarding 
up  the  necessities  of  life.  The  coot*  has  this  peculiarity 
apart  from  other  birds,  that  it  has  a  webbed  foot  for  swim- 
ming, and  a  cloven  foot  for  walking :  for  it  swims  like  a  duck 
in  the  water,  and  walks  like  a  partridge  on  land:  it  drinks 
only  when  it  bites,  since  it  dips  all  its  food  in  water :  it  is  a 
figure  of  the  man  who  will  not  take  advice,  and  does  nothing 
but  what  is  soaked  in  the  water  of  his  own  will.  The  heron,t 
commonly  called  a  falcon,  signifies  those  whose /^^^  are  swift 
to  shed  blood  (Ps.  xiii.  3).  The  plover,  J  which  is  a  garrulous 
bird,  signifies  the  gossip.  The  hoopoe,  which  builds  its  nest 
on  dung,  feeds  on  foetid  ordure,  and  whose  song  is  like  a 
groan,  denotes  worldly  grief  which  works  death  in  those 
who  are  unclean.  The  bat,  which  flies  near  the  ground, 
signifies  those  who  being  gifted  with  worldly  knowledge, 
seek  none  but  earthly  things. — Of  fowls  and  quadrupeds 
those  alone  were  permitted  which  have  the  hind-legs  longer 
than  the  fore-legs,  so  that  they  can  leap :  whereas  those  were 
forbidden  which  cling  rather  to  the  earth:  because  those 
who  abuse  the  doctrine  of  the  four  Evangelists,  so  that  they 
are  not  lifted  up  thereby,  are  reputed  unclean. — By  the 
prohibition  of  blood,  fat  and  nerves,  we  are  to  understand 
the  forbidding  of  cruelty,  lust,  and  bravery  in  committing 
sin. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Men  were  wont  to  eat  plants  and  other 
products  of  the  soil  even  before  the  deluge :  but  the  eating  of 
flesh  seems  to  have  been  introduced  after  the  deluge;  for  it 
is  written  (Gen.  ix.  3) :  Even  as  the  green  herbs  have  I  delivered 
.  .  .  all  flesh  to  you.  The  reason  for  this  was  that  the  eating 
of  the  products  of  the  soil  savours  rather  of  a  simple  life; 
whereas  the  eating  of  flesh  savours  of  delicate  and  over- 
careful  living.  For  the  soil  gives  birth  to  the  herb  of  its 
own  accord ;  and  suchlike  products  of  the  earth  may  be  had 

*  Douay, — porphyrion.  St.  Thomas's  description  tallies  with  the 
coot  or  moorhen:  though  of  course  he  is  mistaken  about  the  feet 
differing  from  one  another. 

t  Vulg., — herodionem. 

j  Here,  again,  the  Douay  translators  transcribed  from  the  Vul- 
gate,— charadrion  ;  charadrius  is  the  generic  name  for  all  plovers. 


219  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      g.  102.  Art.  6 

in  great  quantities  with  very  little  eliort:  whereas  no  small 
trouble  is  necessary  either  to  rear  or  to  catch  an  animal. 
Consequently  God  being  wishful  to  bring  His  people  back  to 
a  more  simple  way  of  living,  forbade  them  to  eat  many  kinds 
of  animals,  but  not  those  things  that  are  produced  by  the 
soil. — Another  reason  may  be  that  animals  were  offered  to 
idols,  while  the  products  of  the  soil  were  not. 

The  Reply  to  the  Third  Objection  is  clear  from  what  has 
been  said  {ad  i). 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  Although  the  kid  that  is  slain  has  no  percep- 
tion of  the  manner  in  which  its  flesh  is  cooked,  yet  it  would 
seem  to  savour  of  heartlessness  if  the  dam's  milk,  which  was 
intended  for  the  nourishment  of  her  offspring,  were  served 
up  on  the  same  dish. — It  might  also  be  said  that  the  Gentiles 
in  celebrating  the  feasts  of  their  idols  prepared  the  flesh  of 
kids  in  this  manner,  for  the  purpose  of  sacrifice  or  banquet : 
hence  (Exod.  xxiii.)  after  the  solemnities  to  be  celebrated 
under  the  Law  had  been  foretold,  it  is  added:  Thou  shalt  7iot 
boil  a  kid  in  the  milk  of  its  dam.  The  figurative  reason  for 
this  prohibition  is  this: — the  kid,  signifying  Christ,  on  ac- 
count of  the  likeness  of  sinful  flesh  (Rom.  viii.  3),  was  not  to 
be  seethed,  i.e.,  slain,  by  the  Jews,  in  the  milk  of  its  dam, 
i.e.,  during  His  infancy. — Or  else  it  signifies  that  the  kid, 
i.e.,  the  sinner,  should  not  be  boiled  in  the  milk  of  its  dam, 
i.e.,  should  not  be  cajoled  by  flattery. 

Reply  Ohj.  5.  The  Gentiles  offered  their  gods  tb.e  first- 
fruits,  which  they  held  to  bring  them  good  luck :  or  they 
burnt  them  for  the  purpose  of  sorcery.  Consequently  (the 
Israelites)  were  commanded  to  look  upon  the  fruits  of  the 
first  three  years  as  unclean:  for  in  that  country  nearly  all 
trees  bear  fruit  in  three  years'  time;  those  trees,  to  wit,  that 
are  cultivated  either  from  seed,  or  from  a  graft  or  from  a 
cutting :  but  it  seldom  happens  that  the  fruit-stones  or  seeds 
encased  in  a  pod  are  sown:  since  it  would  take  a  longer  time 
for  these  to  bear  fruit:  and  the  Law  considered  what  hap- 
pened most  frequently.  The  fruits,  however,  of  the  fourth 
year,  as  being  the  firstlings  of  clean  fruits,  were  offered  to 
God:  and  from  the  fifth  year  onward  they  were  eaten. 


g.  I02.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  220 

The  figurative  reason  was  that  this  foreshadowed  the  fact 
that  after  the  three  states  of  the  Law  (the  first  lasting  from 
Abraham  to  David,  the  second,  until  they  were  carried  away 
to  Babylon,  the  third  until  the  time  of  Christ),  the  Fruit  of 
the  Law,  i.e.,  Christ,  was  to  be  offered  to  God. — Or  again, 
that  we  should  mistrust  our  first  efforts,  on  account  of  their 
imperfection. 

Reply  Ohj.  6.  It  is  said  of  a  man  in  Ecclus.  xix.  27,  that 
the  attire  of  the  body  .  .  .  shows  what  he  is.  Hence  the  Lord 
wished  His  people  to  be  distinguished  from  other  nations, 
not  only  by  the  sign  of  circumcision,  which  was  in  the  flesh, 
but  also  by  a  certain  difference  of  attire.  Wherefore  they 
were  forbidden  to  wear  garments  woven  of  woollen  and  linen 
together,  and  for  a  woman  to  be  clothed  with  man's  apparel, 
or  vice  versa,  for  two  reasons.  First,  to  avoid  idolatrous 
worship.  Because  the  Gentiles,  in  their  religious  rites,  used 
garments  of  this  sort,  made  of  various  materials.  Moreover 
in  the  worship  of  Mars,  women  put  on  men's  armour;  while, 
conversely,  in  the  worship  of  Venus  men  donned  women's 
attire. — The  second  reason  was  to  preserve  them  from  lust: 
because  the  employment  of  various  materials  in  the  making 
of  garments  signified  inordinate  union  of  sexes,  while  the 
use  of  male  attire  by  a  woman,  or  vice  versa,  has  an  incentive 
to  evil  desires,  and  offers  an  occasion  of  lust.  The  figura- 
tive reason  is  that  the  prohibition  of  wearing  a  garment 
woven  of  woollen  and  linen  signified  that  it  was  forbidden 
to  unite  the  simplicity  of  innocence,  denoted  by  wool,  with 
the  duplicity  of  malice,  betokened  by  linen. — It  also  signifies 
that  woman  is  forbidden  to  presume  to  teach,  or  perform 
other  duties  of  men:  or  that  man  should  not  adopt  the 
effeminate  manners  of  a  woman. 

Reply  Ohj.  7.  As  Jerome  says  on  Matth.  xxiii.  6,  the  Lord 
commanded  them  to  make  violet-coloured  fringes  in  the  four 
corners  of  their  garments,  so  that  the  Israelites  might  he  distin- 
guished from  other  nations.  Hence,  in  this  way,  they  pro- 
fessed to  be  Jews:  and  consequently  the  very  sight  of  this 
sign  reminded  them  of  their  Law. 

When  we  read:  Thou  shall  hind  them  on  thy  hand,  and  they 


221  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  6 

shall  he  ever  before  thy  eyes  (Vulg., — they  shall  he  and  shall 
move  between  thy  eyes), — the  Pharisees  gave  a  false  interpreta- 
tion to  these  words,  and  wrote  the  decalogue  of  Moses  on  a 
parchment,  and  tied  it  on  their  foreheads  like  a  wreath,  so  that 
it  moved  in  front  of  their  eyes  :  whereas  the  intention  of  the 
Lord  in  giving  this  commandment  was  that  they  should  be 
bound  in  their  hands,  i.e.,  in  their  works;  and  that  they 
should  be  before  their  eyes,  i.e.,  in  their  thoughts.  The 
violet-coloured  fillets  which  were  inserted  in  their  cloaks 
signify  the  godly  intention  which  should  accompany  our 
every  deed. — It  may,  however,  be  said  that,  because  they 
were  a  carnal-minded  and  stiff-necked  people,  it  was  neces- 
sary for  them  to  be  stirred  by  these  sensible  things  to  the 
observance  of  the  Law. 

Reply  Obj.  8.  Affection  in  man  is  twofold:  it  may  be  an 
affection  of  reason,  or  it  may  be  an  affection  of  passion.  If 
a  man's  affection  be  one  of  reason,  it  matters  not  how  man 
behaves  to  animals,  because  God  has  subjected  all  things  to 
man's  power,  according  to  Ps.  viii.  8 :  Thou  hast  subjected  all 
things  under  his  feet :  and  it  is  in  this  sense  that  the  Apostle 
says  that  God  has  no  care  for  oxen ;  because  God  does  not  ask 
of  man  what  he  does  with  oxen  or  other  animals. 

But  if  man's  affection  be  one  of  passion,  then  it  is  moved 
also  in  regard  to  other  animals:  for  since  the  passion  of  pity 
is  caused  by  the  afflictions  of  others ;  and  since  it  happens 
that  even  irrational  animals  are  sensible  to  pain,  it  is  pos- 
sible for  the  affection  of  pity  to  arise  in  a  man  with  regard 
to  the  sufferings  of  animals.  Now  it  is  evident  that  if  a 
man  practise  a  pitiful  affection  for  animals,  he  is  all  the  more 
disposed  to  take  pity  on  his  fellow-men:  wherefore  it  is 
written  (Pro v.  xii.  10) :  The  just  regardeth  the  lives  of  his 
beasts  :  hut  the  bowels  of  the  wicked  are  cruel.  Consequently 
the  Lord,  in  order  to  inculcate  pity  to  the  Jewish  people, 
who  were  prone  to  cruelty,  wished  them  to  practise  pity  even 
with  regard  to  dumb  animals,  and  forbade  them  to  do  certain 
things  savouring  of  cruelty  to  animals.  Hence  He  pro- 
hibited them  to  boil  a  kid  in  the  milk  of  its  dam  ;  and  to 
muzzle  the  ox  that  treadeth  out  the  corn;  and  to  slay  the  dam 


Q.  I02.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  222 

with  her  young. — It  may,  nevertheless,  be  also  said  that  these 
prohibitions  were  made  in  hatred  of  idolatry.  For  the 
Egyptians  held  it  to  be  wicked  to  allow  the  ox  to  eat  of  the 
grain  while  threshing  the  corn.  Moreover  certain  sorcerers 
were  wont  to  ensnare  the  mother  bird  with  her  young  during 
incubation,  and  to  employ  them  for  the  purpose  of  securing 
fruitfulness  and  good  luck  in  bringing  up  children: — also 
because  it  was  held  to  be  a  good  omen  to  find  the  mother 
sitting  on  her  young. 

As  to  the  mingling  of  animals  of  divers  species,  the  literal 
reason  may  have  been  threefold.  The  first  was  to  show 
detestation  for  the  idolatry  of  the  Egyptians,  who  employed 
various  mixtures  in  worshipping  the  planets,  which  produce 
various  effects,  and  on  various  kinds  of  things  according  to 
their  various  conjunctions. — The  second  reason  was  in  con- 
demnation of  unnatural  sins.  —  The  third  reason  was  the 
entire  removal  of  all  occasions  of  concupiscence.  Because 
animals  of  different  species  do  not  easily  breed,  unless 
this  be  brought  about  by  man;  and  movements  of  lust  are 
aroused  by  seeing  such  things.  Wherefore  in  the  Jewish 
traditions  we  find  it  prescribed,  as  stated  by  Rabbi  Moses, 
that  men  shall  turn  away  their  eyes  from  such  sights. 

The  figurative  reason  for  these  things  is  that  the  necessities 
of  life  should  not  be  withdrawn  from  the  ox  that  treadeth 
the  corn,  i.e.,  from  the  preacher  bearing  the  sheaves  of  doc- 
trine, as  the  Apostle  states  (i  Cor.  ix.  4,  seqq.). — Again,  we 
should  not  take  the  dam  with  her  young :  because  in  certain 
things  we  have  to  keep  the  spiritual  senses,  i.e.,  the  offspring, 
and  set  aside  the  observance  of  the  letter,  i.e.,  the  mother, 
for  instance  in  all  the  ceremonies  of  the  Law.  It  is  also 
forbidden  that  beasts  of  burden,  i.e.,  any  of  the  common 
people,  should  be  allowed  to  engender,  i..e,  to  have  any 
connection,  with  animals  of  another  kind,  i.e.,  with  Gentiles 
or  Jews. 

Reply  Ohj.  9.  All  these  minglings  were  forbidden  in  agri- 
culture; literally,  in  detestation  of  idolatry.  For  the  Egyp- 
tians in  worshipping  the  stars  employed  various  combina- 
tions of  seeds,  animals  and  garments,  in  order  to  represent 


223  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  102.  Art.  6 

the  various  conjunctions  of  the  stars. — Or  else  all  these 
minglings  were  forbidden  in  detestation  of  the  unnatural 
vice. 

They  have,  however,  a  figurative  reason.  For  the  pro- 
hibition :  Thou  shall  not  sow  thy  field  with  different  seeds,  is 
to  be  understood,  in  the  spiritual  sense,  of  the  prohibition 
to  sow  strange  doctrine  in  the  Church,  which  is  a  spiritual 
vineyard. — Likewise  the  field,  i.e.,  the  Church,  must  not  be 
sown  with  different  seeds,  i.e.,  with  Catholic  and  heretical 
doctrines. — Neither  is  it  allowed  to  plough  with  an  ox  and 
an  ass  together  ;  thus  a  fool  should  not  accompany  a  wise  man 
in  preaching,  for  one  would  hinder  the  other. 

Reply  Ohj.  10.*  Silver  and  gold  were  reasonably  forbidden  (Deut. 
vii.)  not  as  though  they  were  not  subject  to  the  power  of  man,  but 
because,  like  the  idols  themselves,  all  materials  out  of  which  idols 
were  made,  were  anathematized  as  hateful  in  God's  sight.  This  is 
clear  from  the  same  chapter,  where  we  read  further  on  (verse  26) : 
Neither  shalt  thou  bring  anything  of  the  idol  into  thy  house,  lest  thou 
become  an  anathema,  like  it.  Another  reason  was  lest,  by  taking 
silver  and  gold,  they  should  be  led  by  avarice  into  idolatry  to  which 
the  Jews  were  inclined.  The  other  precept  (Deut.  xxiii.)  about 
covering  up  excretions,  was  just  and  becoming,  both  for  the  sake  of 
bodily  cleanliness ;  and  in  order  to  keep  the  air  wholesome ;  and  by 
reason  of  the  respect  due  to  the  tabernacle  of  the  covenant  which 
stood  in  the  midst  of  the  camp,  wherein  the  Lord  was  said  to  dwell; 
as  is  clearly  set  forth  in  the  same  passage,  where  after  expressing  the 
command,  the  reason  thereof  is  at  once  added,  to  wit:  For  the  Lord 
thy  God  walketh  in  the  midst  of  thy  camp,  to  deliver  thee,  and  to  give  up 
thy  enemies  to  thee,  and  let  thy  camp  be  holy  [i.e.,  clean),  and  let  no 
uncleanness  appear  therein.  The  figurative  reason  for  this  precept, 
according  to  Gregory  {Moral,  xxxi.).  is  that  sins  which  are  the  fetid 
excretions  of  the  mind  should  be  covered  over  by  repentance,  that  we 
may  become  acceptable  to  God,  according  to  Ps.  xxxi.  i :  Blessed  are 
they  whose  iniquities  are  forgiven  and  whose  sins  are  covered.  Or  else 
according  to  a  gloss,  that  we  should  recognize  the  unhappy  condition 
of  human  nature,  and  humbly  cover  and  purify  the  stains  of  a 
puffed-up  and  proud  spirit  in  the  deep  furrow  of  self-examination. 

Reply  Ohj.  11.  Sorcerers  and  idolatrous  priests  made  use, 
in  their  rites,  of  the  bones  and  flesh  of  dead  men.  Where- 
fore, in  order  to  extirpate  the  customs  of  idolatrous  worship, 
the  Lord  commanded  that  the  priests  of  inferior  degree,  who 
at  fixed  times  served  in  the  temple,  should  not  incur  an 

*  The  Reply  to  the  Tenth  Objection  is  lacking  in  the  codices. 
The  solution  given  here  is  found  in  some  editions,  and  was  supplied 
by  Nicolai. 


Q.  102.  Art.  6     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  224 

uncleanness  at  the  death  of  anyone  except  of  those  who  were 
closely  related  to  them,  viz.,  their  father  or  mother,  and 
others  thus  near  of  kin  to  them.  But  the  high-priest  had 
always  to  be  ready  for  the  service  of  the  sanctuary;  where- 
fore he  was  absolutely  forbidden  to  approach  the  dead,  how- 
ever nearly  related  to  him. — They  were  also  forbidden  to 
marry  a  harlot  or  one  that  has  been  put  away,  or  any  other 
than  a  virgin :  both  on  account  of  the  reverence  due  to  the 
priesthood,  the  honour  of  which  would  seem  to  be  tarnished 
by  such  a  marriage:  and  for  the  sake  of  the  children  who 
would  be  disgraced  by  the  mother's  shame:  which  was  most 
of  all  to  be  avoided  when  the  priestly  dignity  was  passed  on 
from  father  to  son. — Again,  they  were  commanded  to  shave 
neither  head  nor  beard,  and  not  to  make  incisions  in 
their  flesh,  in  order  to  exclude  the  rites  of  idolatry.  For 
the  priests  of  the  Gentiles  shaved  both  head  and  beard, 
wherefore  it  is  written  (Baruch  vi.  30) :  Priests  sit  in  their 
temples  having  their  garments  rent,  and  their  heads  and  beards 
shaven.  Moreover,  in  worshipping  their  idols  they  cut  them- 
selves with  knives  and  lancets  (3  Kings  xviii.  28).  For  this 
reason  the  priests  of  the  Old  Law  were  commanded  to  do 
the  contrary. 

The  spiritual  reason  for  these  things  is  that  priests  should 
be  entirely  free  from  dead  works,  i.e.,  sins.  And  they  should 
not  shave  their  heads,  i.e.,  set  wisdom  aside;  nor  should 
they  shave  their  beards,  i.e.,  set  aside  the  perfection  of 
wisdom;  nor  rend  their  garments  or  cut  their  flesh,  i.e.,  they 
should  not  incur  the  sin  of  schism. 


QUESTION  cm. 

OF  THE  DURATION  OF  THE  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  duration  of  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts: under  which  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  the  ceremonial  precepts  were  in  existence  before 
the  Law  ?  (2)  Whether  at  the  time  of  the  Law  the  cere- 
monies of  the  Old  Law  had  any  power  of  justification  ? 

(3)  Whether    they    ceased    at    the    coming    of    Christ  ? 

(4)  Whether  it  is  a  mortal  sin  to  observe  them  after  the 
coming  of  Christ  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  the  ceremonies  of  the  law  were  in  existence 

before  the  law  ? 

We  proceed  tJms  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  ceremonies  of  the  Law  were 
in  existence  before  the  Law.  For  sacrifices  and  holocausts 
were  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CL, 
A.  4).  But  sacrifices  and  holocausts  preceded  the  Law:  for 
it  is  written  (Gen.  iv.  3,  4)  that  Cain  offered,  of  the  fruits  of 
the  earth,  gifts  to  the  Lord,  and  that  Ahel  offered  of  the  firstlings 
of  his  flock,  and  of  their  fat.  Noe  also  offered  holocausts  to 
the  Lord  (Gen.  xviii.  20),  and  Abraham  did  in  like  manner 
(Gen.  xxii.  13).  Therefore  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law 
preceded  the  Law. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  erecting  and  consecrating  of  the  altar 

were  part  of  the  ceremonies  relating  to  holy  things.     But 

these  preceded  the  Law.     For  we  read  (Gen.  xiii.  18)  that 

A  brahani  .  .  .  built  .  .  .  an  altar  to  the  Lord  ;  and  (Gen. 

II.  3  225  15 


Q.  103.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  226 

xxviii.  18)  that  Jacob  .  .  .  took  the  stone  .  .  .  and  set  it  up 
for  a  title,  pouring  oil  upon  the  top  of  it.  Therefore  the  legal 
ceremonies  preceded  the  Law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  first  of  the  legal  sacraments  seems  to 
have  been  circumcision.  But  circumcision  preceded  the 
Law,  as  appears  from  Gen.  xvii.  In  like  manner  the  priest- 
hood preceded  the  Law;  for  it  is  written  (Gen.  xiv.  18)  that 
Melchisedech  .  .  .  was  the  priest  of  the  most  high  God.  There- 
fore the  sacramental  ceremonies  preceded  the  Law. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  the  distinction  of  clean  from  unclean 
animals  belongs  to  the  ceremonies  of  observances,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  C.  IL,  A.  6  ad  i).  But  this  distinction  preceded  the 
Law;  for  it  is  written  (Gen.  vii.  2,  3) :  Of  all  clean  beasts  take 
seven  and  seven  .  .  .  but  of  the  beasts  that  are  unclean,  two 
and  two.     Therefore  the  legal  ceremonies  preceded  the  Law. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Deut.  vi.  i) :  These  are  the 
precepts,  and  ceremonies  .  .  .  which  the  Lord  your  God  com- 
manded that  I  should  teach  you.  But  they  would  not  have 
needed  to  be  taught  about  these  things,  if  the  aforesaid  cere- 
monies had  been  already  in  existence.  Therefore  the  legal 
ceremonies  did  not  precede  the  Law. 

/  answer  that,  As  is  clear  from  what  has  been  said  (Q.  CI., 
A.  2;  Q.  CIL,  A.  2),  the  legal  ceremonies  were  ordained  for 
a  double  purpose ;  the  worship  of  God,  and  the  foreshadowing 
of  Christ.  Now  whoever  worships  God  must  needs  worship 
Him  by  means  of  certain  fixed  things  pertaining  to  external 
worship.  But  the  fixing  of  the  divine  worship  belongs 
to  the  ceremonies;  just  as  the  determining  of  our  rela- 
tions with  our  neighbour  is  a  matter  determined  by  the 
judicial  precepts,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCIX.,  A.  4).  Conse- 
quently, as  among  men  in  general  there  were  certain  judicial 
precepts,  not  indeed  established  by  Divine  authority,  but 
ordained  by  human  reason;  so  also  there  were  some  cere- 
monies fixed,  not  by  the  authority  of  any  law,  but  according 
to  the  will  and  devotion  of  those  that  worship  God.  Since, 
however,  even  before  the  Law  some  of  the  leading  men  were 
gifted  with  the  spirit  of  prophecy,  it  is  to  be  believed  that 
a  heavenly  instinct,  like  a  private  law,  prompted  them  to 


227  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  103.  Art.  t 

worship  God  in  a  certain  definite  way,  which  would  be  both 
in  keeping  with  the  interior  worship,  and  a  suitable  token  of 
Christ's  mysteries,  which  were  foreshadowed  also  by  other 
things  that  they  did,  according  to  i  Cor.  x.  11:  All  ..  . 
things  happened  to  them  in  figure.  Therefore  there  were  some 
ceremonies  before  the  Law,  but  they  were  not  legal  cere- 
monies, because  they  were  not  as  yet  established  by  legisla- 
tion. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  patriarchs  offered  up  these  oblations, 
sacrifices  and  holocausts  previously  to  the  Law,  out  of  a 
certain  devotion  of  their  own  will,  according  as  it  seemed 
proper  to  them  to  offer  up  in  honour  of  God  those  things 
which  they  had  received  from  Him,  and  thus  to  testify  that 
they  worshipped  God  Who  is  the  beginning  and  end  of  all. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  They  also  established  certain  sacred  things, 
because  they  thought  that  the  honour  due  to  God  demanded 
that  certain  places  should  be  set  apart  from  others  for  the 
purpose  of  divine  worship. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  sacrament  of  circumcision  was  estab- 
lished by  command  of  God  before  the  Law.  Hence  it  cannot 
be  called  a  sacrament  of  the  Law  as  though  it  were  an  insti- 
tution of  the  Law,  but  only  as  an  observance  included  in  the 
Law.  Hence  Our  Lord  said  (John  vii.  22)  that  circumcision 
was  not  of  Moses,  but  of  his  fathers. — Again,  among  those 
who  worshipped  God,  the  priesthood  was  in  existence  before 
the  Law  by  human  appointment,  for  the  Law  allotted  the 
priestly  dignity  to  the  firstborn. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  The  distinction  of  clean  from  unclean 
animals  was  in  vogue  before  the  Law,  not  with  regard  to 
eating  them,  since  it  is  written  (Gen.  ix.  3) :  Everything  that 
moveth  and  liveth  shall  be  meat  for  you  :  but  only  as  to  the 
offering  of  sacrifices,  because  they  used  only  certain  animals 
for  that  purpose.  If,  however,  they  did  make  any  distinc- 
tion in  regard  to  eating;  it  was  not  that  it  was  considered 
illegal  to  eat  such  animals,  since  this  was  not  forbidden  by 
any  law,  but  from  dislike  or  custom :  thus  even  now  we  see 
that  certain  foods  are  looked  upon  with  disgust  in  some 
countries,  while  people  partake  of  them  in  others. 


Q.  103.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  228 

Second  Article. 

whether,  at  the  time  of  the  law,  the  ceremonies  of 
the  old  law  had  any  power  of  justification  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law 
had  the  power  of  justification  at  the  time  of  the  Law. 
Because  expiation  from  sin  and  consecration  pertains  to  justi- 
fication. But  it  is  written  (Exod.  xxix.  21)  that  the  priests 
and  their  apparel  were  consecrated  by  the  sprinkling  of  blood 
and  the  anointing  of  oil;  and  (Levit.  xvi.  16)  that,  by 
sprinkling  the  blood  of  the  calf,  the  priest  expiated  the  sanc- 
tuary from  the  uncleanness  of  the  children  of  Israel,  and  from 
their  transgressions  and  .  .  .  their  sins.  Therefore  the  cere- 
monies of  the  Old  Law  had  the  power  of  justification. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  that  by  which  man  pleases  God  pertains 
to  justification,  according  to  Ps.  x.  8:  The  Lord  is  just  and 
hath  loved  justice.  But  some  pleased  God  by  means  of  cere- 
monies, according  to  Levit.  x.  19 :  How  could  I  .  .  .  please 
the  Lord  in  the  ceremonies,  having  a  sorrowful  heart?  There- 
fore the  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law  had  the  power  of  justifi- 
cation. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  things  relating  to  the  divine  worship 
regard  the  soul  rather  than  the  body,  according  to  Ps. 
xviii.  8 :  The  Law  of  the  Lord  is  unspotted,  converting  souls. 
But  the  leper  was  cleansed  by  means  of  the  ceremonies  of 
the  Old  Law,  as  stated  in  Lev.  xiv.  Much  more  therefore 
could  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law  cleanse  the  soul  by 
justifying  it. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Apostle  says  (Gal.  ii.)*:  If  there  had 
been  a  law  given  which  could  justify  (Vulg., — give  life),  Christ 
died  in  vain,  i.e.,  without  cause.  But  this  is  inadmissible. 
Therefore  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law  did  not  confer 
justice. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CIL,  A.  5  ^^  4),  a  two- 

*  The  first  words  of  the  quotation  are  from  iii.  21 :  St.  Thomas 
probably  quoting  from  memory,  substituted  them  for  ii.  21,  which 
runs  thus:  If  justice  b&  by  the  Law,  then  Christ  died  in  vain. 


229  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  103.  Art.  2 

fold  uncleanness  was  distinguished  in  the  Old  Law.  One 
was  spiritual  and  is  the  uncleanness  of  sin.  The  other  was 
corporal,  which  rendered  a  man  unfit  for  divine  worship; 
thus  a  leper,  or  anyone  that  touched  carrion,  was  said  to  be 
unclean:  and  thus  uncleanness  was  nothing  but  a  kind  of 
irregularity.  From  this  uncleanness,  then,  the  ceremonies 
of  the  Old  Law  had  the  power  to  cleanse :  because  they  were 
ordered  by  the  Law  to  be  employed  as  remedies  for  the 
removal  of  the  aforesaid  uncleannesses  which  were  con- 
tracted in  consequence  of  the  prescription  of  the  Law. 
Hence  the  Apostle  says  (Heb.  ix.  13)  that  the  blood  of  goats 
and  of  oxen,  and  the  ashes  of  a  heifer,  being  spYi}ikled,  sanctify 
such  as  are  defiled,  to  the  cleansing  of  the  flesh.  And  just  as 
this  uncleanness  which  was  washed  away  by  suchlike  cere- 
monies, affected  the  flesh  rather  than  the  soul,  so  also  the 
ceremonies  themselves  are  called  by  the  Apostle  shortly 
before  (verse  10)  justices  of  the  flesh:  justices  of  the  flesh, 
says  he,  being  laid  on  them  until  the  time  of  correction. 

On  the  other  hand,  they  had  no  power  of  cleansing  from 
uncleanness  of  the  soul,  i.e.,  from  the  uncleanness  of  sin. 
The  reason  of  this  was  that  at  no  time  could  there  be  expia- 
tion from  sin,  except  through  Christ,  Who  taketh  away  the 
sins  (Vulg., — sin)  of  the  world  (John  i.  29).  And  since  the 
mystery  of  Christ's  Incarnation  and  Passion  had  not  yet 
really  taken  place,  those  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law  could 
not  really  contain  in  themselves  a  power  flowing  from  Christ 
already  incarnate  and  crucified,  such  as  the  sacraments  of 
the  New  Law  contain.  Consequently  they  could  not  cleanse 
from  sin :  thus  the  Apostle  says  (Heb.  x.  4)  that  it  is  impos- 
sible that  with  the  blood  of  oxen  and  goats  sin  should  be  taken 
away  ;  and  for  this  reason  he  calls  them  (Gal.  iv.  9)  weak 
and  needy  elements  :  weak  indeed,  because  they  cannot  take 
away  sin;  but  this  weakness  results  from  their  being  needy, 
i.e.,  from  the  fact  that  they  do  not  contain  grace  within 
themselves. 

However,  it  was  possible  at  the  time  of  the  Law,  for  the 
minds  of  the  faithful,  to  be  united  by  faith  to  Christ  incar- 
nate and  crucified;  so  that  they  were  justified  by  faith  in 


Q.  103.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  230 

Christ:  of  which  faith  the  observance  of  these  ceremonies 
was  a  sort  of  profession,  inasmuch  as  they  foreshadowed 
Christ.  Hence  in  the  Old  Law  certain  sacrifices  were  offered 
up  for  sins,  not  as  though  the  sacrifices  themselves  washed 
sins  away,  but  because  they  were  professions  of  faith  which 
cleansed  from  sin.  In  fact,  the  Law  itself  implies  this  in 
the  terms  employed:  for  it  is  written  (Lev.  iv.  26,  v.  16)  that 
in  offering  the  sacrifice  for  sin  the  priest  shall  pray  for  him  .  .  . 
and  it  shall  be  forgiven  him,  as  though  the  sin  were  forgiven, 
not  in  virtue  of  the  sacrifices,  but  through  the  faith  and 
devotion  of  those  who  offered  them. — It  must  be  observed, 
however,  that  the  very  fact  that  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old 
Law  washed  away  uncleanness  of  the  body,  was  a  figure  of 
that  expiation  from  sins  which  was  effected  by  Christ. 

It  is  therefore  evident  that  under  the  state  of  the  Old  Law 
the  ceremonies  had  no  power  of  justification. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  That  sanctification  of  priests  and  their  sons, 
and  of  their  apparel  or  of  anything  else  belonging  to  them, 
by  sprinkling  them  with  blood,  had  no  other  effect  but  to 
appoint  them  to  the  divine  worship,  and  to  remove  impedi- 
ments from  them,  to  the  cleansing  of  the  flesh,  as  the  Apostle 
states  (Heb.  ix.  13),  in  token  of  that  sanctification  whereby 
lesus  sanctified  the  people  by  His  own  blood  [ibid.  xiii.  12). — 
Moreover,  the  expiation  must  be  understood  as  referring  to 
the  removal  of  these  bodily  uncleannesses,  not  to  the  forgive- 
ness of  sin.  Hence  even  the  sanctuary  which  could  not  be 
the  subject  of  sin  is  stated  to  be  expiated. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  priests  pleased  God  in  the  ceremonies 
by  their  obedience  and  devotion,  and  by  their  faith  in  the 
reality  foreshadowed ;  not  by  reason  of  the  things  considered 
in  themselves. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Those  ceremonies  which  were  prescribed  in 
the  cleansing  of  a  leper,  were  not  ordained  for  the  purpose 
of  taking  away  the  defilement  of  leprosy.  This  is  clear  from 
the  fact  that  these  ceremonies  were  not  applied  to  a  man 
until  he  was  already  healed :  hence  it  is  written  (Lev.  xiv.  3,  4) 
that  the  priest,  going  out  of  the  camp,  when  he  shall  find  that 
the  leprosy  is  cleansed,  shall  command  him  that  is  to  be  purified 


231  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  103.  Art.  3 

to  offer,  etc. ;  whence  it  is  evident  that  the  priest  was  ap- 
pointed the  judge  of  leprosy,  not  before,  but  after  cleansing. 
But  these  ceremonies  were  employed  for  the  purpose  of 
taking  away  the  uncleanness  of  irregularity.^ — They  do  say, 
however,  that  if  a  priest  were  to  err  in  his  judgment,  the 
leper  would  be  cleansed  miraculously  by  the  power  of  God, 
but  not  in  virtue  of  the  sacrifice.  Thus  also  it  was  by  miracle 
that  the  thigh  of  the  adulterous  woman  rotted,  when  she 
had  drunk  the  water  on  which  the  priest  had  heaped  curses, 
as  stated  in  Num.  v.  19-27. 

Third  Article. 

whether  the  ceremonies  of  the  old  law  ceased  at  the 

coming  of  christ  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law 
did  not  cease  at  the  coming  of  Christ.  For  it  is  written 
(Baruch  iv.  i) :  This  is  the  book  of  the  commandments  of  God, 
and  the  law  that  is  for  ever.  But  the  legal  ceremonies  were 
part  of  the  Law.  Therefore  the  legal  ceremonies  were  to 
last  for  ever. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  offering  made  by  a  leper  after  being 
cleansed  was  a  ceremony  of  the  Law.  But  the  Gospel 
commands  the  leper,  who  has  been  cleansed,  to  make  this 
offering  (Matth.  viii.  4).  Therefore  the  ceremonies  of  the 
Old  Law  did  not  cease  at  Christ's  coming. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  as  long  as  the  cause  remains,  the  effect 
remains.  But  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old  Law  had  certain 
reasonable  causes,  inasmuch  as  they  were  ordained  to  the 
worship  of  God,  besides  the  fact  that  they  were  intended 
to  be  figures  of  Christ.  Therefore  the  ceremonies  of  the  Old 
Law  should  not  have  ceased. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  circumcision  was  instituted  as  a  sign  of 
Abraham's  faith:  the  observance  of  the  sabbath,  to  recall  the 
blessing  of  creation:  and  other  solemnities,  in  memory  of 
other  Divine  favours,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CIL,  A.  4  ad  10; 
A.  5  ^^  i).     But  Abraham's  faith  is  ever  to  be  imitated  even 


Q.  103.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  232 

by  us :  and  the  blessing  of  creation  and  other  Divine  favours 
should  never  be  forgotten.  Therefore  at  least  circumcision 
and  the  other  legal  solemnities  should  not  have  ceased. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Coloss.  ii.  16,  17) :  Let 
no  man  .  .  .  judge  you  in  meat  or  in  drink,  or  in  respect  of 
a  festival  day,  or  of  the  new  moon,  or  of  the  sabbaths,  ivhich 
are  a  shadow  of  things  to  come  :  and  (Heb.  viii.  13) :  In  saying 
a  new  {testament),  he  hath  made  the  former  old  :  and  that 
which  decay eth  and  groweth  old,  is  near  its  end. 

I  answer  that.  All  the  ceremonial  precepts  of  the  Old  Law 
were  ordained  to  the  worship  of  God,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CI., 
A  A.  I,  2).  Now  external  worship  should  be  in  proportion 
to  the  internal  worship,  which  consists  in  faith,  hope,  and 
charity.  Consequently  exterior  worship  had  to  be  subject 
to  variations  according  to  the  variations  in  the  internal 
worship,  in  which  a  threefold  state  may  be  distinguished. 
One  state  was  in  respect  of  faith  and  hope,  both  in  heavenly 
goods,  and  in  the  means  of  obtaining  them, — in  both  of 
these  considered  as  things  to  come.  Such  was  the  state  of 
faith  and  hope  in  the  Old  Law. — Another  state  of  the  in- 
terior worship  is  that  in  which  we  have  faith  and  hope  in 
heavenly  goods  as  things  to  come;  but  in  the  means  of 
obtaining  heavenly  goods,  as  in  things  present  or  past. 
Such  is  the  state  of  the  New  Law. — The  third  state  is  that 
in  which  both  are  possessed  as  present;  wherein  nothing  is 
believed  in  as  lacking,  nothing  hoped  for  as  being  yet  to 
come.     Such  is  the  state  of  the  Blessed. 

In  this  state  of  the  Blessed,  then,  nothing  in  regard  to  the 
worship  of  God  will  be  figurative ;  there  will  be  naught  but 
thanksgiving  and  voice  of  praise  (Isa.  li.  3).  Hence  it  is 
written  concerning  the  city  of  the  Blessed  (Apoc.  xxi.  22) : 
/  saw  no  temple  therein  :  for  the  Lord  God  Almighty  is  the 
temple  thereof,  and  the  Lamb.  Proportionately,  therefore, 
the  ceremonies  of  the  first-mentioned  state  which  fore- 
shadowed the  second  and  third  states,  had  need  to  cease 
at  the  advent  of  the  second  state;  and  other  ceremonies 
had  to  be  introduced  which  would  be  in  keeping  with  the 
state  of  divine  worship  for  that  particular  time,  wherein 


233  CEREMONIAL  PRECICPTS      Q.  i<>3-  Art.  3 

heavenly  goods  are  a  thing  of  the  future,  but  the  Divine 
favours  whereby  we  obtain  the  heavenly  boons  are  a  thing 
of  the  present. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  Old  Law  is  said  to  be /or  ever  simply 
and  absolutely,  as  regards  its  moral  precepts ;  but  as  regards 
the  ceremonial  precepts  it  lasts  for  ever  in  respect  of  the 
reality  which  those  ceremonies  foreshadowed. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  mystery  of  the  redemption  of  the  human 
race  was  fulfilled  in  Christ's  Passion:  hence  Our  Lord  said 
then:  It  is  consummated  (John  xix.  30).  Consequently  the 
prescriptions  of  the  Law  must  have  ceased  then  altogether 
through  their  reality  being  fulfilled.  As  a  sign  of  this,  we 
read  that  at  the  Passion  of  Christ  the  veil  of  the  temple  was 
rent  (Matth.  xxvn.  51).  Hence,  before  Christ's  Passion, 
while  Christ  was  preaching  and  working  miracles,  the  Law 
and  the  Gospel  were  concurrent,  since  the  mystery  of  Christ 
had  already  begun,  but  was  not  as  yet  consummated.  And 
for  this  reason  Our  Lord,  before  His  Passion,  commanded 
the  leper  to  observe  the  legal  ceremonies. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  literal  reasons  already  given  (Q.  CIL) 
for  the  ceremonies  refer  to  the  divine  worship,  which  was 
founded  on  faith  in  that  which  was  to  come.  Hence,  at  the 
advent  of  Him  Who  was  to  come,  both  that  worship  ceased, 
and  all  the  reasons  referring  thereto. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  The  faith  of  Abraham  was  commended  in 
that  he  believed  in  God's  promise  concerning  his  seed  to 
come,  in  which  all  nations  were  to  be  blessed.  Wherefore, 
as  long  as  this  seed  was  yet  to  come,  it  was  necessary  to 
make  profession  of  Abraham's  faith  by  means  of  circum- 
cision. But  now  that  it  is  consummated,  the  same  thing 
needs  to  be  declared  by  means  of  another  sign,  viz.,  Baptism, 
which,  in  this  respect,  took  the  place  of  circumcision,  accord- 
ing to  the  saying  of  the  Apostle  (Coloss.  ii.  11,  12) :  You  are 
circumcised  with  circumcision  not  made  hy  hand,  in  despoiling 
of  the  body  of  the  flesh,  hut  in  the  circumcision  of  Christ,  buried 
with  Him  in  Baptism. 

As  to  the  sabbath,  which  was  a  sign  recalling  the  first 
creation,  its  place  is  taken  by  the  Lord's  Day,  which  recalls 


Q.  103.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  234 

the  beginning  of  the  new  creature  in  the  Resurrection  of 
Christ. — In  Hke  manner  other  solemnities  of  the  Old  Law 
are  supplanted  by  new  solemnities:  because  the  blessings 
vouchsafed  to  that  people,  foreshadowed  the  favours  granted 
us  by  Christ.  Hence  the  feast  of  the  Passover  gave  place 
to  the  feast  of  Christ's  Passion  and  Resurrection:  the  feast 
of  Pentecost  when  the  Old  Law  was  given,  to  the  feast  of 
Pentecost  on  which  was  given  the  Law  of  the  living  spirit: 
the  feast  of  the  New  Moon,  to  Lady  Day,  when  appeared  the 
first  rays  of  the  sun,  i.e.,  Christ,  by  the  fulness  of  grace:  the 
feast  of  Trumpets,  to  the  feasts  of  the  Apostles :  the  feast  of 
Expiation,  to  the  feasts  of  Martyrs  and  Confessors :  the  feast 
of  Tabernacles,  to  the  feast  of  the  Church  Dedication :  the 
feast  of  the  Assembly  and  Collection,  to  feast  of  the  Angels, 
or  else  to  the  feast  of  All  Hallows. 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  since  christ's  passion  the  legal  ceremonies 
can  be  observed  without  committing  mortal  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  since  Christ's  Passion  the  legal 
ceremonies  can  be  observed  without  committing  mortal  sin. 
For  we  must  not  believe  that  the  apostles  committed 
mortal  sin  after  receiving  the  Holy  Ghost:  since  by  His 
fulness  they  were  endued  with  power  from  on  high  (Luke 
xxiv.  49).  But  the  apostles  observed  the  legal  ceremonies 
after  the  coming  of  the  Holy  Ghost:  for  it  is  stated  (Acts 
xvi.  3)  that  Paul  circumcised  Timothy:  and  (Acts  xxi.  26) 
that  Paul,  at  the  advice  of  James,  took  the  men,  and  .  .  . 
being  purified  with  them,  entered  into  the  temple,  giving  notice 
of  the  accomplishment  of  the  days  of  purification,  until  an 
oblation  should  be  offered  for  every  one  of  them.  Therefore 
the  legal  ceremonies  can  be  observed  since  the  Passion  of 
Christ  without  committing  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  one  of  the  legal  ceremonies  consisted  in 
shunning  the  fellowship  of  Gentiles.  But  the  first  Pastor  of 
the  Church  complied  with  this  observance;  for  it  is  stated 


2J5  CKKEMONIAL  PRl£(:i^:iTS      g.  103.  Art.  4 

(Gal.  ii.  12)  that,  when  certain  men  had  come  to  Antioch, 
Peter  withdrew  and  separated  himself  from  the  Gentiles. 
Therefore  the  legal  ceremonies  can  be  observed  since  Christ's 
Passion  without  committing  mortal  sin. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  commands  of  the  apostles  did  not 
lead  men  into  sin.  But  it  was  commanded  by  apostolic 
decree  that  the  Gentiles  should  observe  certain  ceremonies 
of  the  Law:  for  it  is  written  (Acts  xv.  28,  29) :  It  hath  seemed 
good  to  the  Holy  Ghost  and  to  us,  to  lay  no  further  burden  upon 
you  than  these  necessary  things  :  that  you  abstain  from  things 
sacrificed  to  idols,  and  from  blood,  and  from  things  strangled, 
and  from  fornication.  Therefore  the  legal  ceremonies  can 
be  observed  since  Christ's  Passion  without  committing  mortal 
sin. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Gal.  v.  2) :  //  you  he 
circumcised,  Christ  shall  profit  you  nothing.  But  nothing 
save  mortal  sin  hinders  us  from  receiving  Christ's  fruit. 
Therefore  since  Christ's  Passion  it  is  a  mortal  sin  to  be  cir- 
cumcised, or  to  observe  the  other  legal  ceremonies. 

/  answer  that.  All  ceremonies  are  professions  of  faith,  in 
which  the  interior  worship  of  God  consists.  Now  man  can 
make  profession  of  his  inward  faith,  by  deeds  as  well  as  by 
words:  and  in  either  profession,  if  he  make  a  false  declara- 
tion, he  sins  mortally.  Now,  though  our  faith  in  Christ  is 
the  same  as  that  of  the  fathers  of  old;  yet,  since  they  came 
before  Christ,  whereas  we  come  after  Him,  the  same  faith 
is  expressed  in  different  words,  by  us  and  by  them.  For 
by  them  was  it  said:  Behold  a  virgin  shall  conceive  and  bear 
a  son,  where  the  verbs  are  in  the  future  tense:  whereas  we 
express  the  same  by  means  of  verbs  in  the  past  tense,  and 
say  that  she  conceived  and  bore.  In  like  manner  the  cere- 
monies of  the  Old  Law  betokened  Christ  as  having  yet  to 
be  born  and  to  suffer:  whereas  our  sacraments  signify  Him 
as  already  born  and  having  suffered.  Consequently,  just  as  it 
would  be  a  mortal  sin  now  for  anyone,  in  making  a  profes- 
sion of  faith,  to  say  that  Christ  is  yet  to  be  born,  which  the 
fathers  of  old  said  devoutly  and  truthfully;  so  too  it  would 
be  a  mortal  sin  now  to  observe  those  ceremonies  which  the 


Q.  103.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  236 

fathers  of  old  fulfilled  with  devotion  and  fidelity.  Such  is 
the  teaching  of  Augustine  (Contra  Faust,  xix.),  who  says: 
It  is  no  longer  promised  that  He  shall  be  born,  shall  suffer  and 
rise  again,  truths  of  which  their  sacraments  were  a  kind  of 
image  :  but  it  is  declared  that  He  is  already  born,  has  suffered 
and  risen  again  ;  of  which  our  sacraments,  in  which  Christians 
share,  are  the  actual  representation. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  On  this  point  there  seems  to  have  been  a 
difference  of  opinion  between  Jerome  and  Augustine.  For 
Jerome  [Super  Galat.  ii.  11,  seq.)  distinguished  two  periods 
of  time.  One  was  the  time  previous  to  Christ's  Passion, 
during  which  the  legal  ceremonies  were  neither  dead,  since 
they  were  obligatory,  and  did  expiate  in  their  own  fashion; 
nor  deadly,  because  it  was  not  sinful  to  observe  them.  But 
immediately  after  Christ's  Passion  they  began  to  be  not  only 
dead,  so  as  no  longer  to  be  either  effectual  or  binding;  but 
also  deadly,  so  that  whoever  observed  them  was  guilty  of 
mortal  sin.  Hence  he  maintained  that  after  the  Passion 
the  apostles  never  observed  the  legal  ceremonies  in  real 
earnest;  but  only  by  a  kind  of  pious  pretence,  lest,  to  wit, 
they  should  scandalize  the  Jews  and  hinder  their  conversion. 
This  pretence,  however,  is  to  be  understood,  not  as  though 
they  did  not  in  reality  perform  those  actions,  but  in  the 
sense  that  they  performed  them  without  the  mind  to  observe 
the  ceremonies  of  the  Law :  thus  a  man  might  cut  away  his 
foreskin  for  health's  sake,  not  with  the  intention  of  observing 
legal  circumcision. 

But  since  it  seems  unbecoming  that  the  apostles,  in  order 
to  avoid  scandal,  should  have  hidden  things  pertaining  to 
the  truth  of  life  and  doctrine,  and  that  they  should  have 
made  use  of  pretence,  in  things  pertaining  to  the  salvation 
of  the  faithful;  therefore  Augustine  [Epist.  Ixxxii.)  more 
fittingly  distinguished  three  periods  of  time.  One  was  the 
time  that  preceded  the  Passion'  of  Christ,  during  which  the 
legal  ceremonies  were  neither  deadly  nor  dead:  another 
period  was  after  the  publication  of  the  Gospel,  during  which 
the  legal  ceremonies  are  both  dead  and  deadly.  The 
third  is  a  middle  period,  viz.,  from  the  Passion  of  Christ 


237  CEREMONIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  103.  Art.  4 

until  the  publication  of  the  Gospel,  during  which  the 
legal  ceremonies  were  dead  indeed,  because  they  had 
neither  effect  nor  binding  force;  but  were  not  deadly,  because 
it  was  lawful  for  the  Jewish  converts  to  Christianity  to 
observe  them,  provided  they  did  not  put  their  trust  in  them 
so  as  to  hold  them  to  be  necessary  unto  salvation,  as  though 
faith  in  Christ  could  not  justify  without  the  legal  observ- 
ances. On  the  other  hand,  there  was  no  reason  why  those 
who  were  converted  from  heathendom  to  Christianity  should 
observe  them.  Hence  Paul  circumcised  Timothy,  who  was 
born  of  a  Jewish  mother;  but  was  unwilling  to  circumcise 
Titus,  who  was  of  heathen  nationality. 

The  reason  why  the  Holy  Ghost  did  not  wish  the  con- 
verted Jews  to  be  debarred  at  once  from  observing  the  legal 
ceremonies,  while  converted  heathens  were  forbidden  to 
observe  the  rites  of  heathendom,  was  in  order  to  show  that 
there  is  a  difference  between  these  rites.  For  heathenish 
ceremonial  was  rejected  as  absolutely  unlawful,  and  as  pro- 
hibited by  God  for  all  time;  whereas  the  legal  ceremonial 
ceased  as  being  fulfilled  through  Christ's  Passion,  being 
instituted  by  God  as  a  figure  of  Christ. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  According  to  Jerome,  Peter  withdrew  him- 
self from  the  Gentiles  by  pretence,  in  order  to  avoid  giving 
scandal  to  the  Jews,  of  whom  he  was  the  Apostle.  Hence 
he  did  not  sin  at  all  in  acting  thus.  On  the  other  hand, 
Paul  in  like  manner  made  a  pretence  of  blaming  him,  in 
order  to  avoid  scandalizing  the  Gentiles,  whose  Apostle  he 
was. — But  Augustine  disapproves  of  this  solution:  because 
in  the  canonical  Scripture  (viz..  Gal.  ii.  11),  wherein  we  must 
not  hold  anything  to  be  false,  Paul  says  that  Peter  was  to  be 
blamed.  Consequently  it  is  true  that  Peter  was  at  fault: 
and  Paul  blamed  him  in  very  truth  and  not  with  pretence. 
Peter,  however,  did  not  sin,  by  observing  the  legal  cere- 
monial for  the  time  being;  because  this  was  lawful  for  him 
who  was  a  converted  Jew.  But  he  did  sin  by  excessive 
minuteness  in  the  observance  of  the  legal  rites  lest  he  should 
scandalize  the  Jews,  the  result  being  that  he  gave  scandal 
to  the  Gentiles. 


Q.  103.  Art.  4      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  238 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Some  have  held  that  this  prohibition  of  the 
apostles  is  not  to  be  taken  literally,  but  spiritually :  namely, 
that  the  prohibition  of  blood  signifies  the  prohibition  of 
murder ;  the  prohibition  of  things  strangled,  that  of  violence 
and  rapine;  the  prohibition  of  things  offered  to  idols,  that 
of  idolatry;  while  fornication  is  forbidden  as  being  evil  in 
itself:  which  opinion  they  gathered  from  certain  glosses, 
which  expound  these  prohibitions  in  a  mystical  sense. — Since, 
however,  murder  and  rapine  were  held  to  be  unlawful  even 
by  the  Gentiles,  there  would  have  been  no  need  to  give  this 
special  commandment  to  those  who  were  converted  to  Christ 
from  heathendom.  Hence  others  maintain  that  those  foods 
were  forbidden  literally,  not  to  prevent  the  observance  of 
legal  ceremonies,  but  in  order  to  prevent  gluttony.  Thus 
Jerome  says  on  Ezech.  xliv.  31  [The  priest  shall  not  eat  of 
anything  that  is  dead)  :  He  condemns  those  priests  who  from 
gluttony  did  not  keep  these  precepts. 

But  since  certain  foods  are  more  delicate  than  these  and 
more  conducive  to  gluttony,  there  seems  no  reason  why 
these  should  have  been  forbidden  more  than  the  others. 

We  must  therefore  follow  the  third  opinion,  and  hold 
that  these  foods  were  forbidden  literally,  not  with  the  pur- 
pose of  enforcing  compliance  with  the  legal  ceremonies,  but 
in  order  to  further  the  union  of  Gentiles  and  Jews  living  side 
by  side.  Because  blood  and  things  strangled  were  loath- 
some to  the  Jews  by  ancient  custom ;  while  the  Jews  might 
have  suspected  the  Gentiles  of  relapse  into  idolatry  if  the 
latter  had  partaken  of  things  offered  to  idols.  Hence  these 
things  were  prohibited  for  the  time  being,  during  which  the 
Gentiles  and  Jews  were  to  become  united  together.  But  as 
time  went  on,  with  the  lapse  of  the  cause,  the  effect  lapsed 
also,  when  the  truth  of  the  Gospel  teaching  was  divulged, 
wherein  Our  Lord  taught  that  not  that  which  entereth  into 
the  mouth  defileth  a  man  (Matth.  xv.  11) ;  and  that  nothing 
is  to  he  rejected  that  is  received  with  thanksgiving  (i  Tim.  iv.  4). 
— With  regard  to  fornication  a  special  prohibition  was  made, 
because  the  Gentiles  did  not  hold  it  to  be  sinful. 


QUESTION  CIV. 

OF  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  judicial  precepts:  and  first  of  all 
we  shall  consider  them  in  general;  in  the  second  place  we 
shall  consider  their  reasons.  Under  the  first  head  there  are 
four  points  of  inquir}^:  (i)  What  is  meant  by  the  judicial 
precepts  ?  (2)  Whether  they  are  figurative  ?  (3)  Their 
duration.     (4)  Their  division. 

First  Article. 

whether  the  judicial  precepts  were  those  which 
directed  man  in  relation  to  his  neighbour  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  judicial  precepts  were  not 
those  which  directed  man  in  his  relations  to  his  neighbour. 
For  judicial  precepts  take  their  name  from  judgme^it.  But 
there  are  many  things  that  direct  man  as  to  his  neighbour, 
which  are  not  subordinate  to  judgment.  Therefore  the 
judicial  precepts  were  not  those  which  directed  man  in  his 
relations  to  his  neighbour. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  judicial  precepts  are  distinct  from 
the  moral  precepts,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCIX.,  A.  4).  But 
there  are  many  moral  precepts  which  direct  man  as  to  his 
neighbour:  as  is  evidently  the  case  with  the  seven  precepts 
of  the  second  table.  Therefore  the  judicial  precepts  are  not 
so  called  from  directing  man  as  to  his  neighbour. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  as  the  ceremonial  precepts  relate  to  God, 
so  do  the  judicial  precepts  relate  to  one's  neighbour,  as  stated 

239 


Q.  104.  Art.  t      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  240 

above  (Q.  XCIX.,  A.  4;  Q.  CL,  A.  i).  But  among  the  cere- 
monial precepts  there  are  some  which  concern  man  himself, 
such  as  observances  in  matter  of  food  and  apparel,  of  which 
we  have  already  spoken  (Q.  CIL,  A.  6  ad  i,  6).  Therefore 
the  judicial  precepts  are  not  so  called  from  directing  man  as 
to  his  neighbour. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  reckoned  (Ezech.  xviii.  8)  among 
other  works  of  a  good  and  just  man,  that  he  hath  executed 
trite  judgment  between  man  and  man.  But  judicial  precepts 
are  so  called  from  judgment.  Therefore  it  seems  that  the 
judicial  precepts  were  those  which  directed  the  relations 
between  man  and  man. 

I  answer  that,  As  is  evident  from  what  we  have  stated 
above  (Q.  XCV.,  A.  2;  Q.  XCIX.,  A.  4),  in  every  law,  some 
precepts  derive  their  binding  force  from  the  dictate  of  reason 
itself,  because  natural  reason  dictates  that  something  ought 
to  be  done  or  to  be  avoided.  These  are  called  moral  pre- 
cepts :  since  human  morals  are  based  on  reason. — At  the  same 
time  there  are  other  precepts  which  derive  their  binding 
force,  not  from  the  very  dictate  of  reason  (because,  con- 
sidered in  themselves,  they  do  not  imply  an  obligation  of 
something  due  or  undue) ;  but  from  some  institution,  Divine 
or  human :  and  such  are  certain  determinations  of  the  moral 
precepts.  When  therefore  the  moral  precepts  are  fixed  by 
Divine  institution  in  matters  relating  to  man's  subordination 
to  God,  they  are  called  ceremonial  precepts :  but  when  they 
refer  to  man's  relations  to  other  men,  they  are  called  judicial 
precepts.  Hence  there  are  two  conditions  attached  to  the 
judicial  precepts :  viz.,  first,  that  they  refer  to  man's  relations 
to  other  men ;  secondly,  that  they  derive  their  binding  force 
not  from  reason  alone,  but  in  virtue  of  their  institution. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Judgments  emanate  through  the  official  pro- 
nouncement of  certain  men  who  are  at  the  head  of  affairs, 
and  in  whom  the  judicial  power  is  vested.  Now  it  belongs 
to  those  who  are  at  the  head  of  affairs  to  regulate  not  only 
litigious  matters,  but  also  voluntary  contracts  which  are 
concluded  between  man  and  man,  and  whatever  matters 
concern  the  community  at  large  and  the  government  thereof. 


241  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  104.  Ari.  i 

Consequently  the  judicial  precepts  are  not  only  those  which 
concern  actions  at  law;  but  also  all  those  that  are  directed 
to  the  ordering  of  one  man  in  relation  to  another,  which 
ordering  is  subject  to  the  direction  of  the  sovereign  as 
supreme  judge. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  argument  holds  in  respect  of  those 
precepts  which  direct  man  in  his  relations  to  his  neighbour, 
and  derive  their  binding  force  from  the  mere  dictate  of 
reason. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Even  in  those  precepts  which  direct  us  to 
God,  some  are  moral  precepts,  which  the  reason  itself  dictates 
when  it  is  quickened  by  faith ;  such  as  that  God  is  to  be  loved 
and  worshipped.  There  are  also  ceremonial  precepts,  which 
have  no  binding  force  except  in  virtue  of  their  Divine  institu- 
tion. Now  God  is  concerned  not  only  with  the  sacrifices 
that  are  offered  to  Him,  but  also  with  whatever  relates  to 
the  fitness  of  those  who  offer  sacrifices  to  Him  and  worship 
Him.  Because  men  are  ordained  to  God  as  to  their  end; 
wherefore  it  concerns  God  and,  consequently,  is  a  matter  of 
ceremonial  precept,  that  man  should  show  some  fitness  for 
the  divine  worship.  On  the  other  hand,  man  is  not  ordained 
to  his  neighbour  as  to  his  end,  so  as  to  need  to  be  disposed 
in  himself  with  regard  to  his  neighbour,  for  such  is  the  rela- 
tionship of  a  slave  to  his  master,  since  a  slave  is  his  master's 
in  all  that  he  is,  as  the  Philosopher  says  [Polit.  i.).  Hence 
there  are  no  judicial  precepts  ordaining  man  in  himself;  all 
such  precepts  are  moral:  because  the  reason,  which  is  the 
principle  in  moral  matters,  holds  the  same  position,  in  man, 
with  regard  to  things  that  concern  him,  as  a  prince  or  judge 
holds  in  the  state. — Nevertheless  we  must  take  note  that, 
since  the  relations  of  man  to  his  neighbour  are  more  subject 
to  reason  than  the  relations  of  man  to  God,  there  are  more 
precepts  whereby  man  is  directed  in  his  relations  to  his 
neighbour,  than  whereby  he  is  directed  to  God.  For  the 
same  reason  there  had  to  be  more  ceremonial  than  judicial 
precepts  in  the  Law. 


n.  3  16 


Q.  104.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  242 

Second  Article, 
whether  the  judicial  precepts  were  figurative  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  judicial  precepts  were  not 
figurative.  Because  it  seems  proper  to  the  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts to  be  instituted  as  figures  of  something  else.  There- 
fore, if  the  judicial  precepts  are  figurative,  there  will  be  no 
difference  between  the  judicial  and  ceremonial  precepts. 

Ohj,  2.  Further,  just  as  certain  judicial  precepts  were 
given  to  the  Jewish  people,  so  also  were  some  given  to  other 
heathen  peoples.  But  the  judicial  precepts  given  to  other 
peoples  were  not  figurative,  but  stated  what  had  to  be  done. 
Therefore  it  seems  that  neither  were  the  judicial  precepts  of 
the  Old  Law  figures  of  anything. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  those  things  which  relate  to  the  divine 
worship  had  to  be  taught  under  certain  figures,  because  the 
things  of  God  are  above  our  reason,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CI., 
A.  2,  ad  2),  But  things  concerning  our  neighbour  are  not 
above  our  reason.  Therefore  the  judicial  precepts  which 
direct  us  in  relation  to  our  neighbour  should  not  have  been 
figurative. 

On  the  contrary,  The  judicial  precepts  are  expounded  both 
in  the  allegorical  and  in  the  moral  sense  (Exod.  xxi.). 

/  answer  that,  A  precept  may  be  figurative  in  two  ways. 
First,  primarily  and  in  itself:  because,  to  wit,  it  is  instituted 
principally  that  it  may  be  the  figure  of  something.  In  this 
way  the  ceremonial  precepts  are  figurative ;  since  they  were 
instituted  for  the  very  purpose  that  they  might  foreshadow 
something  relating  to  the  worship  of  God  and  the  mystery 
of  Christ. — But  some  precepts  are  figurative,  not  primarily 
and  in  themselves,  but  consequently.  In  this  way  the 
judicial  precepts  of  the  Old  Law  are  figurative.  For  they 
were  not  instituted  for  the  purpose  of  being  figurative,  but 
in  order  that  they  might  regulate  the  state  of  that  people 
according  to  justice  and  equity.  Nevertheless  they  did 
foreshadow  something  consequently:  since,  to  wit,  the  entire 
state  of  that  people,  who  were  directed  by  these  precepts, 


243  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  104.  Art.  3 

was  tigurative,  according  to  i  Cor.  x.  11:  All  .  .  .  things 
happened  to  thcni  in  figure. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  ceremonial  precepts  are  not  figurative 
in  the  same  way  as  the  judicial  precepts,  as  explained  above. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  Jewish  people  were  chosen  by  God  that 
Christ  might  be  born  of  them.  Consequently  the  entire 
state  of  that  people  had  to  be  prophetic  and  figurative,  as 
Augustine  states  {Contra  Faust,  xxii.).  For  this  reason 
even  the  judicial  precepts  that  were  given  to  this  people 
were  more  figurative  than  those  which  were  given  to  other 
nations.  Thus,  too,  the  wars  and  deeds  of  this  people  are 
expounded  in  the  mystical  sense :  but  not  the  wars  and  deeds 
of  the  Assyrians  or  Romans,  although  the  latter  are  more 
famous  in  the  eyes  of  men. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  this  people  the  direction  of  man  in  regard 
to  his  neighbour,  considered  in  itself,  was  subject  to  reason. 
But  in  so  far  as  it  was  referred  to  the  worship  of  God,  it 
was  above  reason :  and  in  this  respect  it  was  figurative. 

Third  Article, 
whether  the  judicial  precepts  of  the  old  law  bind 

FOR   EVER  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  judicial  precepts  of  the  Old 
Law  bind  for  ever.  Because  the  judicial  precepts  relate  to 
the  virtue  of  justice:  since  a  judgment  is  an  execution  of 
the  virtue  of  justice.  Now  justice  is  perpetual  and  immortal 
(Wis.  i.  15).     Therefore  the  judicial  precepts  bind  for  ever. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Divine  institutions  are  more  enduring 
than  human  institutions.  But  the  judicial  precepts  of 
human  laws  bind  for  ever.  Therefore  much  more  do  the 
judicial  precepts  of  the  Divine  Law. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  xApostle  says  (Heb.  vii.  18)  that  there  is 
a  setting  aside  of  the  former  commandment,  because  of  the 
weakness  and  unprofitableness  thereof.  Now  this  is  true  of 
the  ceremonial  precept,  which  could  (Vulg., — can)  not,  as  to 
the  conscience,  make  him  perfect  that  serveth  only  in  meats  and 


Q.  104.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  244 

in  drinks,  and  divers  washings  and  justices  of  the  flesh,  as  the 
Apostle  declares  (Heb.  ix.  9,  10).  On  the  other  hand,  the 
judicial  precepts  were  useful  and  efficacious  in  respect  of 
the  purpose  for  which  they  were  instituted,  viz.,  to  establish 
justice  and  equity  among  men.  Therefore  the  judicial 
precepts  of  the  Old  Law  are  not  set  aside,  but  still  retain 
their  efficacy. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Apostle  says  (Heb.  vii.  12)  that  the 
priesthood  being  translated  it  is  necessary  that  a  translation 
also  be  made  of  the  Law.  But  the  priesthood  was  transferred 
from  Aaron  to  Christ.  Therefore  the  entire  Law  was  also 
transferred.  Therefore  the  judicial  precepts  are  no  longer  in 
force. 

/  answer  that,  The  judicial  precepts  did  not  bind  for  ever, 
but  were  annulled  by  the  coming  of  Christ :  yet  not  in  the 
same  way  as  the  ceremonial  precepts.  For  the  ceremonial 
precepts  were  annulled  so  far  as  to  be  not  only  dead,  but  also 
deadly  to  those  who  observe  them  since  the  coming  of  Christ, 
especially  since  the  promulgation  of  the  Gospel.  On  the 
other  hand,  the  judicial  precepts  are  dead  indeed,  because 
they  have  no  binding  force:  but  they  are  not  deadly.  For 
if  a  sovereign  were  to  order  these  judicial  precepts  to  be 
observed  in  his  kingdom,  he  would  not  sin:  unless  perchance 
they  were  observed,  or  ordered  to  be  observed,  as  though 
they  derived  their  binding  force  through  being  institutions 
of  the  Old  Law:  for  it  would  be  a  deadly  sin  to  intend  to 
observe  them  thus. 

The  reason  for  this  difference  may  be  gathered  from  what 
has  been  said  above  (A.  2).  For  it  has  been  stated  that  the 
ceremonial  precepts  are  figurative  primarily  and  in  them- 
selves, as  being  instituted  chiefly  for  the  purpose  of  fore- 
shadowing the  mysteries  of  Christ  to  come. — On  the  other 
hand,  the  judicial  precepts  were  not  instituted  that  they 
might  be  figures,  but  that  they  might  shape  the  state  of 
that  people  who  were  directed  to  Christ.  Consequently, 
when  the  state  of  that  people  changed  with  the  coming  of 
Christ,  the  judicial  precepts  lost  their  binding  force:  for  the 
Law  was  a  pedagogue,  leading  men  to  Christ,  as  stated  in 


245  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  lo^.  Art.  3 

Gal.  iii.  24.  Since,  however,  these  judicial  precepts  are 
instituted,  not  for  the  purpose  of  being  figures,  but  for  th(3 
performance  of  certain  deeds,  the  observance  thereof  is  not 
prejudicial  to  the  truth  of  faith.  But  the  intention  of 
observing  them,  as  though  one  were  bound  by  the  Law,  is 
prejudicial  to  the  truth  of  faith:  because  it  would  follow  that 
the  former  state  of  the  people  still  lasts,  and  that  Christ  has 
not  yet  come. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  obligation  of  observing  justice  is  indeed 
perpetual.  But  the  determination  of  those  things  that  are 
just,  according  to  human  or  Divine  institution,  must  needs 
be  different,  according  to  the  different  states  of  mankind. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  judicial  precepts  established  by  men 
retain  their  binding  force  for  ever,  so  long  as  the  state  of 
government  remains  the  same.  But  if  the  state  or  nation 
pass  to  another  form  of  government,  the  laws  must  needs 
be  changed.  For  democracy,  which  is  government  by  the 
people,  demands  different  laws  from  those  of  oligarchy, 
which  is  government  by  the  rich,  as  the  Philosopher  shows 
{Polit.  iv.).  Consequently  when  the  state  of  that  people 
changed,  the  judicial  precepts  had  to  be  changed  also. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Those  judicial  precepts  directed  the  people 
to  justice  and  equity,  in  keeping  with  the  demands  of  that 
state.  But  after  the  coming  of  Christ,  there  had  to  be  a 
change  in  the  state  of  that  people,  so  that  in  Christ  there 
was  no  distinction  between  Gentile  and  Jew,  as  there  had 
been  before.  For  this  reason  the  judicial  precepts  needed 
to  be  changed  also. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  it  is  possible  to  assign  a  distinct  division 
of  the  judicial  precepts  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  it  is  impossible  to  assign  a 
distinct  division  of  the  judicial  precepts.  Because  the 
judicial  precepts  direct  men  in  their  relations  to  one  another. 
But  those  things  which  need  to  be  directed,  as  pertaining  to 


Q.  104.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  246 

the  relationship  between  man  and  man,  and  which  are  made 
use  of  by  men,  are  not  subject  to  division,  since  they  are 
infinite  in  number.  Therefore  it  is  not  possible  to  assign 
a  distinct  division  of  the  judicial  precepts. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  judicial  precepts  are  decisions  on 
moral  matters.  But  moral  precepts  do  not  seem  to  be 
capable  of  division,  except  in  so  far  as  they  are  reducible  to 
the  precepts  of  the  decalogue.  Therefore  there  is  no  distinct 
division  of  the  judicial  precepts. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  because  there  is  a  distinct  division  of  the 
ceremonial  precepts,  the  Law  alludes  to  this  division,  by 
describing  some  as  sacrifices,  others  as  observances.  But  the 
Law  contains  no  allusion  to  a  division  of  the  judicial  pre- 
cepts. Therefore  it  seems  that  they  have  no  distinct 
division. 

On  the  contrary,  Wherever  there  is  order  there  must  needs 
be  division.  But  the  notion  of  order  is  chiefly  applicable 
to  the  judicial  precepts,  since  thereby  that  people  was 
ordained.  Therefore  it  is  most  necessary  that  they  should 
have  a  distinct  division. 

I  answer  that,  Since  law  is  the  art,  as  it  were,  of  directing 
or  ordering  the  life  of  man,  as  in  every  art  there  is  a  distinct 
division  in  the  rules  of  art,  so,  in  every  law,  there  must  be 
a  distinct  division  of  precepts:  else  the  law  would  be  ren- 
dered useless  by  confusion.  We  must  therefore  say  that 
the  judicial  precepts  of  the  Old  Law,  whereby  men  were 
directed  in  their  relations  to  one  another,  are  subject  to 
division  according  to  the  divers  ways  in  which  man  is 
directed. 

Now  in  every  people  a  fourfold  order  is  to  be  found:  one, 
of  the  people's  sovereign  to  his  subjects;  a  second,  of  the 
subjects  among  themselves  ;  a  third,  of  the  citizens  to 
foreigners;  a  fourth,  of  members  of  the  same  household, 
such  as  the  order  of  the  father  to  his  son;  of  the  wife 
to  her  husband ;  of  the  master  to  his  servant :  and  according 
to  these  four  orders  we  may  distinguish  different  kinds  of 
judicial  precepts  in  the  Old  Law.  For  certain  precepts  are 
laid  down  concerning  the  institution  of  the  sovereign  and 


247  THE  JUDICIAL  PRFXEPTS      Q.  104.  Art.  4 

relating  to  his  office,  and  about  the  respect  due  to  him :  this 
is  one  part  of  the  judicial  precepts. — Again,  certain  precepts 
are  given  in  respect  of  a  man  to  his  fellow  citizens:  for 
instance,  about  buying  and  selling,  judgments  and  penalties: 
this  is  the  second  part  of  the  judicial  precepts. — Again, 
certain  precepts  are  enjoined  with  regard  to  foreigners:  for 
instance,  about  wars  waged  against  their  foes,  and  about  the 
way  to  receive  travellers  and  strangers:  this  is  the  third 
part  of  the  judicial  precepts. — Lastly,  certain  precepts  are 
given  relating  to  home  life:  for  instance,  about  servants, 
wives  and  children:  this  is  the  fourth  part  of  the  judicial 
precepts. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Things  pertaining  to  the  ordering  of  relations 
between  one  man  and  another  are  indeed  infinite  in  number : 
yet  they  are  reducible  to  certain  distinct  heads,  according  to 
the  different  relations  in  which  one  man  stands  to  another, 
as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  precepts  of  the  decalogue  held  the  first 
place  in  the  moral  order,  as  stated  above  (Q.  C,  A.  3) :  and 
consequently  it  is  fitting  that  other  moral  precepts  should 
be  distinguished  in  relation  to  them.  But  the  judicial  and 
ceremonial  precepts  have  a  different  binding  force,  derived, 
not  from  natural  reason,  but  from  their  institution  alone. 
Hence  there  is  a  distinct  reason  for  distinguishing  them. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  Law  alludes  to  the  division  of  the 
judicial  precepts  in  the  very  things  themselves  which  are 
prescribed  by  the  judicial  precepts  of  the  Law. 


QUESTION  CV. 

OF  THE  REASON  FOR  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  reason  for  the  judicial  precepts: 
under  which  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Con- 
cerning the  reason  for  the  judicial  precepts  relating  to  the 
rulers.  (2)  Concerning  the  fellowship  of  one  man  with 
another.  (3)  Concerning  matters  relating  to  foreigners. 
(4)  Concerning  things  relating  to  domestic  matters. 

First  Article. 

whether  the  old  law  enjoined  fitting  precepts 
concerning  rulers  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  made  unfitting 
precepts  concerning  rulers.  Because,  as  the  Philosopher 
says  {Polit.  iii.),  the  ordering  of  the  people  depends  mostly  on 
the  chief  ruler.  But  the  Law  contains  no  precept  relating 
to  the  institution  of  the  chief  ruler ;  and  yet  we  find  therein 
prescriptions  concerning  the  inferior  rulers:  firstly  (Exod. 
xviii.  21) :  Provide  out  of  all  the  people  wise  (Vulg., — able) 
men,  etc. ;  again  (Num.  xi.  16) :  Gather  unto  Me  seventy  men  of 
the  ancients  of  Israel ;  and  again  (Deut.  i.  13) :  Let  Me  have 
from  among  you  wise  and  understanding  men,  etc.  Therefore 
the  Law  provided  insufficiently  in  regard  to  the  rulers  of 
the  people. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  The  best  gives  of  the  best,  as  Plato  states 
{Tim.  ii.).  Now  the  best  ordering  of  a  state  or  of  any  nation 
is  to  be  ruled  by  a  king:  because  this  kind  of  government 

248 


249  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  105.  Art.  i 

approaches  nearest  in  resemblance  to  the  Divine  govern- 
ment, whereby  God  rules  the  world  from  the  beginning. 
Therefore  the  Law  should  have  set  a  king  over  the  people, 
and  they  should  not  have  been  allowed  a  choice  in  the  matter, 
as  indeed  they  were  allowed  (Deut.  xvii.  14,  15) :  When  thou 
.  .  .  shall  say  :  I  will  set  a  king  over  me  .  .  .  thou  shall  set 
him,  etc. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  according  to  Matth.  xii.  25 :  Every  kingdom 
divided  against  itself  shall  he  made  desolate  :  a  saying  which 
was  verified  in  the  Jewish  people,  whose  destruction  was 
brought  about  by  the  division  of  the  kingdom.  But  the 
Law  should  aim  chiefly  at  things  pertaining  to  the  general 
well-being  of  the  people.  Therefore  it  should  have  forbidden 
the  kingdom  to  be  divided  under  two  kings :  nor  should  this 
have  been  introduced  even  by  Divine  authority;  as  we  read 
of  its  being  introduced  by  the  authority  of  the  prophet 
Ahias  the  Silonite  (3  Kings  xi.  29  seq.). 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  just  as  priests  are  instituted  for  the  benefit 
of  the  people  in  things  concerning  God,  as  stated  in  Heb. 
V.  i;  so  are  rulers  set  up  for  the  benefit  of  the  people  in 
human  affairs.  But  certain  things  were  allotted  as  a  means 
of  livelihood  for  the  priests  and  Levites  of  the  Law :  such  as 
the  tithes  and  first-fruits,  and  many  like  things.  Therefore 
in  like  manner  certain  things  should  have  been  determined 
for  the  livelihood  of  the  rulers  of  the  people:  the  more  that 
they  were  forbidden  to  accept  presents,  as  is  clearly  stated 
in  Exod.  xxiii.  8:  You  shall  not  (Vulg., — Neither  shall  thou) 
take  bribes,  which  even  blind  the  wise,  and  pervert  the  words  of 
the  just. 

Ohj.  5.  Further,  as  a  kingdom  is  the  best  form  of  govern- 
ment, so  is  tyranny  the  most  corrupt.  But  when  the  Lord 
appointed  the  king,  He  established  a  tyrannical  law;  for  it 
is  wTitten  (i  Kings  viii.  11) :  This  will  be  the  right  of  the  king, 
that  shall  reign  over  you  :  He  will  take  your  sons,  etc.  There- 
fore the  Law  made  unfitting  provision  with  regard  to  the 
institution  of  rulers. 

On  the  contrary,  The  people  of  Israel  is  commended  for 
the  beauty  of  its  order  (Num.  xxiv.  5) :  How  beautiful  are 


Q.  105.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  ''  250 

thy  tabernacles,  0  Jacob,  and  thy  tents,  0  Israel.  But  the 
beautiful  ordering  of  a  people  depends  on  the  right  establish- 
ment of  its  rulers.  Therefore  the  Law  made  right  provision 
for  the  people  with  regard  to  its  rulers. 

/  answer  that,  Two  points  are  to  be  observed  concerning 
the  right  ordering  of  rulers  in  a  state  or  nation.  One  is  that 
all  should  take  some  share  in  the  government :  for  this  form 
of  constitution  ensures  peace  among  the  people,  commends 
itself  to  all,  and  is  most  enduring,  as  stated  in  Polit.  ii.  The 
other  point  is  to  be  observed  in  respect  of  the  kinds  of 
government,  or  the  different  ways  in  which  the  constitutions 
are  established.  For  whereas  these  differ  in  kind,  as  the 
Philosopher  states  (Polit.  iii.),  nevertheless  the  first  place 
is  held  by  the  kingdom,  where  the  power  of  government  is 
vested  in  one ;  and  aristocracy,  which  signifies  government  by 
the  best,  where  the  power  of  government  is  vested  in  a  few. 
Accordingly,  the  best  form  of  government  is  in  a  state  or 
kingdom,  wherein  one  is  given  the  power  to  preside  over  all; 
while  under  him  are  others  having  governing  powers:  and 
yet  a  government  of  this  kind  is  shared  by  all,  both  because 
all  are  eligible  to  govern,  and  because  the  rulers  are  chosen 
by  all.  For  this  is  the  best  form  of  polity,  being  partly 
kingdom,  since  there  is  one  at  the  head  of  all;  partly  aris- 
tocracy, in  so  far  as  a  number  of  persons  are  set  in  authority; 
partly  democracy,  i.e.,  government  by  the  people,  in  so  far 
as  the  rulers  can  be  chosen  from  the  people,  and  the  people 
have  the  right  to  choose  their  rulers. 

Such  was  the  form  of  government  established  by  the 
Divine  Law.  For  Moses  and  his  successors  governed  the 
people  in  such  a  way  that  each  of  them  was  ruler  over  all ; 
so  that  there  was  a  kind  of  kingdom.  Moreover,  seventy- 
two  men  were  chosen,  who  were  elders  in  virtue:  for  it  is 
written  (Deut.  i.  15) :  I  took  out  of  your  tribes  men  wise  and 
honourable,  and  appointed  them  rulers  :  so  that  there  was  an 
element  of  aristocracy.  But  it  was  a  democratical  govern- 
ment in  so  far  as  the  rulers  were  .chosen  from  all  the  people ; 
for  it  is  written  (Exod.  xviii.  21) :  Provide  out  of  all  the  people 
wise  (Vulg., — able)  men,  etc.;  and,  again,  in  so  far  as  they 


251  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  105.  Art.  i 

were  chosen  by  the  people;  wherefore  it  is  written  (Deut. 
i.  13):  Let  me  have  from  among  you  wise  (Vulg., — able)  men, 
etc.  Consequently  it  is  evident  that  the  ordering  of  the 
rulers  was  well  provided  for  by  the  Law. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  people  was  governed  under  the  special 
care  of  God:  wherefore  it  is  written  (Deut.  vii.  6) :  The  Lord 
thy  God  hath  chosen  thee  to  he  His  peculiar  people  :  and  this 
is  why  the  Lord  reserved  to  Himself  the  institution  of  the 
chief  ruler.  For  this  too  did  Moses  pray  (Num.  xxvii.  16) : 
May  the  Lord  the  God  of  the  spirits  of  all  the  flesh  provide  a 
man,  that  may  he  over  this  multitude.  Thus  by  God's  orders 
Josue  was  set  at  the  head  in  place  of  Moses:  and  we  read 
about  each  of  the  judges  who  succeeded  Josue  that  God 
raised  .  .  .  up  a  saviour  for  the  people,  and  that  the  spirit 
of  the  Lord  was  in  them  (Judges  iii.  9,  10,  15).  Hence  the 
Lord  did  not  leave  the  choice  of  a  king  to  the  people;  but 
reserved  this  to  Himself,  as  appears  from  Deut.  xvii.  15: 
Thou  shall  set  him  whom  the  Lord  thy  God  shall  choose. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  kingdom  is  the  best  form  of  government 
of  the  people,  so  long  as  it  is  not  corrupt.  But  since  the 
power  granted  to  a  king  is  so  great,  it  easily  degenerates  into 
tyranny,  unless  he  to  whom  this  power  is  given  be  a  very 
virtuous  man :  for  it  is  only  the  virtuous  man  that  conducts 
himself  well  in  the  midst  of  prosperity,  as  the  Philosopher 
observes  [Ethic,  iv.).  Now  perfect  virtue  is  to  be  found  in 
few:  and  especially  were  the  Jews  inclined  to  cruelty  and 
avarice,  which  vices  above  all  turn  men  into  tyrants.  Hence 
from  the  very  first  the  Lord  did  not  set  up  the  kingly 
authority  with  full  power,  but  gave  them  judges  and  gover- 
nors to  rule  them.  But  afterwards  when  the  people  asked 
Him  to  do  so,  being  indignant  with  them,  so  to  speak,  He 
granted  them  a  king,  as  is  clear- from  His  words  to  Samuel 
(i  Kings  viii.  7) :  They  have  not  rejected  thee,  hut  Me,  that  I 
should  not  reign  over  them. 

Nevertheless,  as  regards  the  appointment  of  a  king,  He 
did  establish  the  manner  of  election  from  the  very  beginning 
(Deut.  xvii.  14,  seqq.):  and  then  He  determined  two  points: 
first,  that  in  choosing  a  king  they  should  wait  for  the  Lord's 


Q.  105.  Art.  t     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  252 

decision;  and  that  they  should  not  make  a  man  of  another 
nation  king,  because  such  kings  are  wont  to  take  Httle 
interest  in  the  people  they  are  set  over,  and  consequently  to 
have  no  care  for  their  welfare : — secondly.  He  prescribed  how 
the  king  after  his  appointment  should  behave,  in  regard  to 
himself;  namely,  that  he  should  not  accumulate  chariots 
and  horses,  nor  wives,  nor  immense  wealth :  because  through 
craving  for  such  things  princes  become  tyrants  and  forsake 
justice. — He  also  appointed  the  manner  in  which  they  were 
to  conduct  themselves  towards  God:  namely,  that  they 
should  continually  read  and  ponder  on  God's  Law,  and 
should  ever  fear  and  obey  God. — Moreover,  He  decided 
how  they  should  behave  towards  their  subjects:  namely, 
that  they  should  not  proudly  despise  them,  or  ill-treat 
them,  and  that  they  should  not  depart  from  the  paths  of 
justice. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  division  of  the  kingdom,  and  a  number 
of  kings,  was  rather  a  punishment  inflicted  on  that  people 
for  their  many  dissensions,  specially  against  the  just  rule  of 
David,  than  a  benefit  conferred  on  them  for  their  profit. 
Hence  it  is  written  (Osee  xiii.  11) :  /  will  give  thee  a  king  in  My 
wrath  ;  and  [ibid.  viii.  4) :  They  have  reigned,  hut  not  by  Me: 
they  have  been  princes,  and  I  knew  not. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  The  priestly  ofhce  was  bequeathed  by  suc- 
cession from  father  to  son:  and  this,  in  order  that  it  might 
be  held  in  greater  respect,  if  not  any  man  from  the  people 
could  become  a  priest :  since  honour  was  given  to  them  out 
of  reverence  for  the  divine  worship.  Hence  it  was  necessary 
to  put  aside  certain  things  for  them  both  as  to  tithes  and  as 
to  first-fruits,  and,  again,  as  to  oblations  and  sacrifices,  that 
they  might  be  afforded  a  means  of  livelihood.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  rulers,  as  stated  above,  were  chosen  from  the 
whole  people;  wherefore  they  had  their  own  possessions, 
from  which  to  derive  a  living :  and  so  much  the  more,  since 
the  Lord  forbade  even  a  king  to  have  superabundant  wealth 
for  to  make  too  much  show  of  magnificence :  both  because 
he  could  scarcely  avoid  the  excesses  of  pride  and  tyranny, 
arising  from  such  things,  and  because,  if  the  rulers  were  not 


253  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS      o.  105.  Art.  2 

very  rich,  and  il  their  office  involved  much  work  and  anxiety, 
it  would  not  tempt  the  ambition  of  the  common  people; 
and  would  not  become  an  occasion  of  sedition. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  That  right  was  not  given  to  the  king  by 
Divine  institution:  rather  was  it  foretold  that  kings  would 
usurp  that  right,  by  framing  unjust  laws,  and  by  degener- 
ating into  tyrants  who  preyed  on  their  subjects.  This  is 
clear  from  the  context  that  follows:  And  yoti  shall  be  his 
slaves  (Douay,  servants) :  which  is  signilicative  of  tyranny, 
since  a  tyrant  rules  his  subjects  as  though  they  were  his 
slaves.  Hence  Samuel  spoke  these  words  to  deter  them 
from  asking  for  a  king;  since  the  narrative  continues:  But 
the  people  would  not  hear  the  voice  of  Samuel. — It  may  happen, 
however,  that  even  a  good  king,  without  being  a  tyrant, 
may  take  away  the  sons,  and  make  them  tribunes  and 
centurions;  and  may  take  many  things  from  his  subjects 
in  order  to  secure  the  common  weal. 


Second  x\rticle. 

whether  the  judicial  precepts  were  suitably  framed 
as  to  the  relations  of  one  man  with  another  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  judicial  precepts  were  not 
suitably  framed  as  regards  the  relations  of  one  man  with 
another.  Because  men  cannot  live  together  in  peace,  if  one 
man  takes  what  belongs  to  another.  But  this  seems  to  have 
been  approved  by  the  Law :  since  it  is  written  (Deut.  xxiii.  24) : 
Going  into  thy  neighbour's  vineyard,  thou  mayst  eat  as  many 
grapes  as  thou  pleasest.  Therefore  the  Old  Law  did  not  make 
suitable  provisions  for  man's  peace. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  one  of  the  chief  causes  of  the  downfall 
of  states  has  been  the  holding  of  property  by  women,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  {Polit.  ii.).  But  this  was  introduced  by 
the  Old  Law;  for  it  is  written  (Num.  xxvii.  8) :  When  a  man 
dieth  without  a  son,  his  inheritance  shall  pass  to  his  daughter. 
Therefore  the  Law  made  unsuitable  provision  for  the  welfare 
of  the  people. 


c).  105.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  254 

Obj.  3.  Further,  it  is  most  conducive  to  the  preservation 
of  human  society  that  men  may  provide  themselves  with 
necessaries  by  buying  and  sclHng,  as  stated  in  Polit.  i. 
But  the  Old  Law  took  away  the  force  of  sales;  since  it  pre- 
scribes that  in  the  50th  year  of  the  jubilee  all  that  is  sold 
shall  return  to  the  vendor  (Levit.  xxv.  28).  Therefore  in 
this  matter  the  Law  gave  the  people  an  unfitting  com- 
mand. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  man's  needs  require  that  men  should  be 
ready  to  lend:  which  readiness  ceases  if  the  creditors  do 
not  return  the  pledges:  hence  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  xxix.  10) : 
Many  have  refused  to  lend,  not  out  of  wickedness,  but  they 
were  afraid  to  be  defrauded  without  cause.  And  yet  this 
was  encouraged  by  the  Law.  First,  because  it  prescribed 
(Deut.  XV.  2) :  He  to  whom  any  thing  is  owing  from  his  friend 
or  neighbour  or  brother,  cannot  demand  it  again,  because  it  is 
the  year  of  remission  of  the  Lord  ;  and  (Exod.  xxii.  15)  it  is 
stated  thaf  if  a  borrowed  animal  should  die  while  the  owner 
is  present,  the  borrower  is  not  bound  to  make  restitution. 
Secondly,  because  the  security  acquired  through  the  pledge 
is  lost:  for  it  is  wTitten  (Deut.  xxiv.  10):  When  thou  shalt 
demand  of  thy  neighbour  any  thing  that  he  oweth  thee,  thou 
shalt  not  go  into  his  house  to  take  away  a  fledge  ;  and  again 
(verses  12,  13) :  The  fledge  shall  not  lodge  with  thee  that  night, 
but  thou  shalt  restore  it  to  him  fresently.  Therefore  the  Law 
made  insufficient  provision  in  the  matter  of  loans. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  considerable  risk  attaches  to  goods 
deposited  with  a  fraudulent  depositary:  wherefore  great 
caution  should  be  observed  in  such  matters:  hence  it  is 
stated  in  2  Mach.  iii.  15  that  the  friests  .  .  .  called  ufon 
Him  from  heaven.  Who  made  the  law  concerning  things  given 
to  be  keft,  that  He  would  f reserve  them  safe,  for  them  that 
had  defosited  them.  But  the  precepts  of  the  Old  Law 
observed  little  caution  in  regard  to  deposits:  since  it  is 
prescribed  (Exod.  xxii.  10,  11)  that  when  goods  deposited 
are  lost,  the  owner  is  to  stand  by  the  oath  of  the  depositary. 
Therefore  the  Law  made  unsuitable  provision  in  this  matter. 
Obj.  6.  Further,  just  as  a  workman  offers  his  work  for 


255  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS      Q.  105.  Art.  2 

hire,  so  do  men  let  houses  and  so  forth.  But  there  is  no 
need  for  the  tenant  to  pay  his  rent  as  soon  as  he  takes  a 
house.  Therefore  it  seems  an  unnecessarily  hard  prescrip- 
tion (Lev.  xix.  13)  that  the  wages  of  him  that  hath  been  hired 
by  thee  shall  not  abide  with  thee  until  the  morning. 

Obj.  7.  Further,  since  there  is  often  pressing  need  for  a 
judge,  it  should  be  easy  to  gain  access  to  one.  It  was  there- 
fore unfitting  that  the  Law  (Deut.  xvii.  8,  9)  should  com- 
mand them  to  go  to  a  fixed  place  to  ask  for  judgment  on 
doubtful  matters. 

Obj.  8.  Further,  it  is  possible  that  not  only  two,  but 
three  or  more,  should  agree  to  tell  a  lie.  Therefore  it  is 
unreasonably  stated  (Deut.  xix.  15)  that  in  the  mouth  of  two 
or  three  witnesses  every  word  shall  stand. 

Obj.  9.  Further,  punishment  should  be  fixed  according 
to  the  gravity  of  the  fault:  for  which  reason  also  it  is  written 
(Deut.  XXV.  2):  According  to  the  measure  of  the  sin,  shall  the 
measure  also  of  the  stripes  be.  Yet  the  Law  fixed  unequal 
punishments  for  certain  faults:  for  it  is  wTitten  (Exod. 
xxii.  i)  that  the  thief  shall  restore  five  oxen  for  one  ox,  and 
four  sheep  for  one  sheep.  Moreover,  certain  slight  offences 
are  severely  punished:  thus  (Num.  xv.  32,  seqq.)  a  man  is 
stoned  for  gathering  sticks  on  the  sabbath  day:  and  (Deut. 
xxi.  18,  seqq)  the  unruly  son  is  commanded  to  be  stoned  on 
account  of  certain  small  transgressions,  viz.,  because  he 
gave  himself  to  revelling  .  .  .  and  banquetings.  Therefore 
the  Law  prescribed  punishments  in  an  unreasonable  manner. 

Obj.  10.  Further,  as  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei.  xxi.), 
Tully  writes  that  the  laws  recognize  eight  forms  of  punish- 
ment, indemnity,  prison,  sir c  pes,  retaliation,  public  disgrace, 
exile,  death,  slavery.  Now  some  of  these  were  prescribed 
by  the  Law.  Indemnity,  as  when  a  thief  was  condemned 
to  make  restitution  fivefold  or  fourfold.  Prison,  as  when 
(Num.  XV.  34)  a  certain  man  is  ordered  to  be  imprisoned. 
Stripes;  thus  (Deut.  xxv.  2),  if  they  see  that  the  offender 
be  worthy  of  stripes  ;  they  shall  lay  him  down,  and  shall  cause 
him  to  be  beaten  before  them.  Public  disgrace  was  brought 
on  to  him  who  refused  to  take  to  himself  the  wife  of  his 


g.  105.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  256 

deceased  brother,  for  she  took  off  his  shoe  from  his  foot,  and 
did  spit  in  his  face  [ibid.  9).  It  prescribed  the  death  penalty, 
as  is  clear  from  Lev.  xx.  9:  He  that  curseth  his  father,  or 
mother,  dying  let  him  die.  The  Law  also  recognized  the 
lex  talionis,  by  prescribing  (Exod.  xxi.  24) :  Eye  for  eye, 
tooth  for  tooth.  Therefore  it  seems  unreasonable  that  the 
Law  should  not  have  inflicted  the  two  other  punishments, 
viz.,  exile  and  slavery. 

Obj.  II.  Further,  no  punishment  is  due  except  for  a 
fault.  But  dumb  animals  cannot  commit  a  fault.  There- 
fore the  Law  is  unreasonable  in  punishing  them  (Exod. 
xxi.  29) :  //  the  ox  .  .  .  shall  kill  a  man  or  a  woman,  it 
shall  be  stoned  :  and  (Lev.  xx.  16) :  The  woman  that  shall 
lie  under  any  beast,  shall  be  killed  together  with  the  same. 
Therefore  it  seems  that  matters  pertaining  to  the  relations 
of  one  man  with  another  were  unsuitably  regulated  by  the 
Law. 

Obj.  12.  Further,  the  Lord  commanded  (Exod.  xxi.  12) 
a  murderer  to  be  punished  with  death.  But  the  death  of  a 
dumb  animal  is  reckoned  of  much  less  account  than  the 
slaying  of  a  man.  Hence  murder  cannot  be  sufficiently 
punished  by  the  slaying  of  a  dumb  animal.  Therefore  it  is 
unfittingly  prescribed  (Deut.  xxi.  i,  4)  that  when  there  shall 
be  found  .  .  .  the  corpse  of  a  man  slain,  and  it  is  not  known 
who  is  guilty  of  the  murder  .  .  .  the  ancients  of  the  nearest 
city  shall  take  a  heifer  of  the  herd,  that  hath  not  drawn  in  the 
yoke,  nor  ploughed  the  ground,  and  they  shall  bring  her  into 
a  rough  and  stony  valley,  that  never  was  ploughed,  nor  sown  ; 
and  there  they  shall  strike  off  the  head  of  the  heifer. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  recalled  as  a  special  blessing  (Ps. 
cxlvii.  20)  that  He  hath  not  done  in  like  manner  to  every 
nation  ;  and  His  judgments  He  hath  not  made  manifest  to 
them. 

I  answer  that.  As  Augustine  says  [De  Civ.  Dei.  ii.),  quoting 
Tully,  a  nation  is  a  body  of  men  united  together  by  consent  to 
the  law  and  by  community  of  welfare.  Consequently  it  is  of 
the  essence  of  a  nation  that  the  mutual  relations  of  the 
citizens  be  ordered  by  just  laws.      Now  the  relations  of  one 


257  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS    Q.  105.  Art.  2 

man  with  another  are  twofold :  some  are  effected  under  the 
guidance  of  those  in  authority:  others  are  effected  by  the 
will  of  private  individuals.  And  since  whatever  is  subject 
to  the  power  of  an  individual  can  be  disposed  of  according 
to  his  will,  hence  it  is  that  the  decision  of  matters  between 
one  man  and  another,  and  the  punishment  of  evildoers, 
depend  on  the  direction  of  those  in  authority,  to  whom  men 
are  subject.  On  the  other  hand,  the  power  of  private 
persons  is  exercised  over  the  things  they  possess:  and  con- 
sequently their  dealings  with  one  another,  as  regards  such 
things,  depend  on  their  own  will,  for  instance  in  buying, 
selling,  giving,  and  so  forth.  Now  the  Law  provided  suffi- 
ciently in  respect  of  each  of  these  relations  between  one 
man  and  another.  For  it  established  judges,  as  is  clearly 
indicated  in  Deut.  xvi.  18:  Thou  shalt  appoint  judges  and 
magistrates  in  all  its  (Vulg., — thy)  gates,  .  .  .  that  they  may 
judge  the  -people  with  just  judgment.  It  also  directed  the 
manner  of  pronouncing  just  judgments,  according  to 
Deut.  i.  16,  17:  Judge  that  which  is  just,  whether  he  he  one 
of  your  own  country  or  a  stranger  :  there  shall  he  no  difference 
of  persons.  It  also  removed  an  occasion  of  pronouncing 
unjust  judgment,  by  forbidding  judges  to  accept  bribes 
(Exod.  xxiii.  8;  Deut.  xvi.  19).  It  prescribed  the  number 
of  witnesses,  viz.,  two  or  three:  and  it  appointed  certain 
punishments  to  certain  crimes,  as  we  shall  state  farther  on 
[ad  10). 

But  with  regard  to  possessions,  it  is  a  very  good  thing, 
says  the  Philosopher  [Polit.  ii.)  that  the  things  possessed 
should  be  distinct,  and  that  the  use  thereof  should  be  partly 
common,  and  partly  granted  to  others  by  the  will  of  the 
possessors.  These  three  points  were  provided  for  by  the 
Law.  Because,  in  the  first  place,  the  possessions  themselves 
were  divided  among  individuals:  for  it  is  written  (Num. 
xxxiii.  53,  54) :  /  have  given  you  the  land  for  a  possession  : 
and  you  shall  divide  it  among  you  hy  lot.  And  since  many 
states  have  been  ruined  through  want  of  regulations  in  the 
matter  of  possessions,  as  the  Philosopher  observes  [Polit.  ii.) ; 
therefore  the  Law  provided  a  threefold  remedy  against  the 

n-3  17 


Q.  105.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  258 

irregularity  of  possessions.  The  first  was  that  they  should 
be  divided  equally,  wherefore  it  is  written  (Num.  xxxiii.  54) : 
To  the  more  you  shall  give  a  larger  part,  and  to  the  fewer,  a 
lesser.  A  second  remedy  was  that  possessions  could  not  be 
alienated  for  ever,  but  after  a  certain  lapse  of  time  should 
return  to  their  former  owner,  so  as  to  avoid  confusion  of 
possessions  (c/.  ad  3).  The  third  remedy  aimed  at  the 
removal  of  this  confusion,  and  provided  that  the  dead 
should  be  succeeded  by  their  next  of  kin:  in  the  first  place, 
the  son;  secondly,  the  daughter;  thirdly,  the  brother; 
fourthly,  the  father's  brother;  fifthly,  any  other  next  of  kin. 
Furthermore,  in  order  to  preserve  the  distinction  of 
property,  the  Law  enacted  that  heiresses  should  marry 
within  their  own  tribe,  as  recorded  in  Num.  xxxvi,  6. 

Secondly,  the  Law  commanded  that,  in  some  respects, 
the  use  of  things  should  belong  to  all  in  common.  Firstly, 
as  regards  the  care  of  them;  for  it  was  prescribed  (Deut. 
xxii.  1-4).  Thou  shalt  not  pass  by,  if  thou  seest  thy  brother's 
ox  or  his  sheep  go  astray  ;  but  thou  shalt  bring  them  back  to 
thy  brother,  and  in  like  manner  as  to  other  things. — Secondly, 
as  regards  fruits.  For  all  alike  were  allowed  on  entering  a 
friend's  vineyard  to  eat  of  the  fruit,  but  not  to  take  any 
away.  And,  specially,  with  respect  to  the  poor,  it  was  pre- 
scribed that  the  forgotten  sheaves,  and  the  bimches  of  grapes 
and  fruit,  should  be  left  behind  for  them  (Lev.  xix.  9; 
Deut.  xxiv.  19).  Moreover,  whatever  grew  in  the  seventh 
year  was  common  property,  as  stated  in  Exod.  xxiii.  11  and 
Lev.  XXV.  4. 

Thirdly,  the  law  recognized  the  transference  of  goods  by 
the  owner.  There  was  a  purely  gratuitous  transfer:  thus 
it  is  written  (Deut.  xiv.  28,  29):  The  third  day  thou  shalt 
separate  another  tithe  .  .  .  and  the  Levite  .  .  .  and  the 
stranger,  and  the  fatherless,  and  the  widow  .  .  .  shall  come 
and  shall  eat  and  be  filled.  And  there  was  a  transfer  for  a 
consideration,  for  instance,  by  selling  and  buying,  by  letting 
out  and  hiring,  by  loan  and  also  by  deposit,  concerning 
all  of  which  we  find  that  the  Law  made  ample  provision. 
Consequently  it  is  clear  that  the  Old  Law  provided  suffi- 


259  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS    Q.  105.  Art.  2 

ciently  concerning  the  mutual  relations  of  one  man  with 
another. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  xiii.  8),  he  that 
loveth  his  neighbour  hath  fulfilled  the  Law  :  because,  to  wit, 
all  the  precepts  of  the  Law,  chiefly  those  concerning  our 
neighbour,  seem  to  aim  at  the  end  that  men  should  love 
one  another.  Now  it  is  an  effect  of  love  that  men  give  their 
own  goods  to  others:  because,  as  stated  in  i  John  iii.  17: 
He  that  .  .  .  shall  see  his  brother  in  need,  and  shall  shut  up 
his  bowels  from  him  :  how  doth  the  charity  of  God  abide  in  him  ? 
Hence  the  purpose  of  the  Law  was  to  accustom  men  to  give 
of  their  own  to  others  readily:  thus  the  Apostle  (i  Tim.  vi.  18) 
commands  the  rich  to  give  easily  and  to  communicate  to 
others.  Now  a  man  does  not  give  easily  to  others  if  he 
will  not  suffer  another  man  to  take  some  little  thing  from 
him  without  any  great  injury  to  him.  And  so  the  Law 
laid  down  that  it  should  be  lawful  for  a  man,  on  entering 
his  neighbour's  vineyard,  to  eat  of  the  fruit  there:  but  not 
to  carry  any  away,  lest  this  should  lead  to  the  infliction  of  a 
grievous  harm,  and  cause  a  disturbance  of  the  peace:  for 
among  well-behaved  people,  the  taking  of  a  little  does  not 
disturb  the  peace;  in  fact,  it  rather  strengthens  friendship 
and  accustoms  men  to  give  things  to  one  another. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  Law  did  not  prescribe  that  women 
should  succeed  to  their  father's  estate  except  in  default  of 
male  issue:  failing  which  it  was  necessary  that  succession 
should  be  granted  to  the  female  line  in  order  to  comfort  the 
father,  who  would  have  been  sad  to  think  that  his  estate 
would  pass  to  strangers.  Nevertheless  the  Law  observed 
due  caution  in  the  matter,  by  providing  that  those  women 
who  succeeded  to  their  father's  estate,  should  marry  within 
their  own  tribe,  in  order  to  avoid  confusion  of  tribal  pos- 
sessions, as  stated  in  Num.  xxxvi.  7,  8. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Polit.  ii.),  the 
regulation  of  possessions  conduces  much  to  the  preservation 
of  a  state  or  nation.  Consequently,  as  he  himself  observes, 
it  was  forbidden  by  the  law  in  some  of  the  heathen  states, 
that  anyone  should  sell    his  possessions,  except  to  avoid  a 


Q.  105.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  260 

manifest  loss.  For  if  possessions  were  to  be  sold  indis- 
criminately, they  might  happen  to  come  into  the  hands  of  a 
few :  so  that  it  might  become  necessary  for  a  state  or  country 
to  become  void  of  inhabitants.  Hence  the  Old  Law,  in 
order  to  remove  this  danger,  ordered  things  in  such  a  way 
that  while  provision  was  made  for  men's  needs,  by  allowing 
the  sale  of  possessions  to  avail  for  a  certain  period,  at  the 
same  time  the  said  danger  was  removed,  by  prescribing 
the  return  of  those  possessions  after  that  period  had  elapsed. 
The  reason  for  this  law  was  to  prevent  confusion  of  posses- 
sions, and  to  ensure  the  continuance  of  a  definite  distinction 
among  the  tribes. 

But  as  the  town  houses  were  not  allotted  to  distinct 
estates,  therefore  the  Law  allowed  them  to  be  sold  in  per- 
petuity, like  moveable  goods.  Because  the  number  of 
houses  in  a  town  was  not  fixed,  whereas  there  was  a  fixed 
limit  to  the  amount  of  estates,  which  could  not  be  exceeded, 
while  the  number  of  houses  in  a  town  could  be  increased. 
On  the  other  hand,  houses  situated  not  in  a  town,  but  in  a 
village  that  hath  no  walls,  could  not  be  sold  in  perpetuity: 
because  such  houses  are  built  merely  with  a  view  to  the  cul- 
tivation and  care  of  possessions ;  wherefore  the  Law  rightly 
made  the  same  prescription  in  regard  to  both  (Lev.  xxv.). 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  As  stated  above  {ad  i),  the  purpose  of  the 
Law  was  to  accustom  men  to  its  precepts,  so  as  to  be  ready 
to  come  to  one  another's  assistance:  because  this  is  a  very 
great  incentive  to  friendship.  The  Law  granted  these 
facilities  for  helping  others  in  the  matter  not  only  of  gratui- 
tous and  absolute  donations,  but  also  of  mutual  transfers: 
because  the  latter  kind  of  succour  is  more  frequent  and 
benefits  the  greater  number:  and  it  granted  facilities  for 
this  purpose  in  many  ways.  First  of  all  by  prescribing  that 
men  should  be  ready  to  lend,  and  that  they  should  not  be 
less  inclined  to  do  so  as  the  year  of  remission  drew  nigh,  as 
stated  in  Deut.  xv.  7,  seqq. — Secondly,  by  forbidding  them 
to  burden  a  man  to  whom  they  might  grant  a  loan,  either 
by  exacting  usury,  or  by  accepting  necessities  of  life  in 
security;  and  by  prescribing  that  when  this  had  been  done 


26i  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  105.  Art.  2 

they  should  be  restored  at  once.  For  it  is  written  (Deut. 
xxiii.  19) :  Thou  shall  not  lend  to  thy  brother  money  to  usury  : 
and  (xxiv.  6) :  Thou  shalt  not  take  the  nether  nor  the  upper 
millstone  to  pledge  ;  for  he  hath  pledged  his  life  to  thee  :  and 
(Exod.  xxii.  26) :  If  thou  take  of  thy  neighbour  a  garment  in 
pledge,  thou  shalt  give  it  him  again  before  sunset. — Thirdly, 
by  forbidding  them  to  be  importunate  in  exacting  payment. 
Hence  it  is  written  (Exod.  xxii.  25) :  If  thou  lend  money  to 
any  of  my  people  that  is  poor  that  dwelleth  with  thee,  thou 
shalt  not  be  hard  upon  them  as  an  extortioner.  For  this  reason, 
too,  it  is  enacted  (Deut.  xxiv.  10,  11) :  When  thou  shalt 
demajid  of  thy  neighbour  anything  that  he  oweth  thee,  thou 
shalt  not  go  into  his  house  to  take  away  a  pledge,  but  thou  shalt 
stand  without,  and  he  shall  bring  out  to  thee  what  he  hath  : 
both  because  a  man's  house  is  his  surest  refuge,  wherefore 
it  is  offensive  to  a  man  to  be  set  upon  in  his  own  house ;  and 
because  the  Law  does  not  allow  the  creditor  to  take  away 
whatever  he  likes  in  security,  but  rather  permits  the  debtor 
to  give  what  he  needs  least. — Fourthly,  the  Law  prescribed 
that  debts  should  cease  altogether  after  the  lapse  of  seven 
years.  For  it  was  probable  that  those  who  could  con- 
veniently pay  their  debts,  would  do  so  before  the  seventh 
year,  and  would  not  defraud  the  lender  without  cause. 
But  if  they  were  altogether  insolvent,  there  was  the  same 
reason  for  remitting  the  debt  from  love  for  them,  as  there 
was  for  renewing  the  loan  on  account  of  their  need. 

As  regards  animals  granted  in  loan,  the  Law  enacted 
that  if,  through  the  neglect  of  the  person  to  whom  they 
were  lent,  they  perished  or  deteriorated  in  his  absence,  he 
was  bound  to  make  restitution.  But  if  they  perished  or 
deteriorated  while  he  was  present  and  taking  proper  care 
of  them,  he  was  not  bound  to  make  restitution,  especially 
if  they  were  hired  for  a  consideration:  because  they  might 
have  died  or  deteriorated  in  the  same  way  if  they  had 
remained  in  possession  of  the  lender,  so  that  if  the  animal  had 
been  saved  through  being  lent,  the  lender  would  have  gained 
something  by  the  loan  which  would  no  longer  have  been 
gratuitous.     And  especially  was  this  to  be  observed  when 


Q.  105.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  262 

animals  were  hired  for  a  consideration:  because  then  the 
owner  received  a  certain  price  for  the  use  of  the  animals; 
wherefore  he  had  no  right  to  any  profit,  by  receiving  in- 
demnity for  the  animal,  unless  the  person  who  had  charge 
of  it  were  negligent.  In  the  case,  however,  of  animals  not 
hired  for  a  consideration,  equity  demanded  that  he  should 
receive  something  by  way  of  restitution  at  least  to  the  value 
of  the  hire  of  the  animal  that  had  perished  or  deteriorated. 

Reply  Ohj.  5.  The  difference  between  a  loan  and  a  deposit 
is  that  a  loan  is  in  respect  of  goods  transferred  for  the  use 
of  the  person  to  whom  they  are  transferred,  whereas  a 
deposit  is  for  the  benefit  of  the  depositor.  Hence  in  certain 
cases  there  was  a  stricter  obligation  of  returning  a  loan 
than  of  restoring  goods  held  in  deposit.  Because  the  latter 
might  be  lost  in  two  ways.  First,  unavoidably:  i.e.,  either 
through  a  natural  cause,  for  instance  if  an  animal  held  in 
deposit  were  to  die  or  depreciate  in  value;  or  through  an 
extrinsic  cause,  for  instance,  if  it  were  taken  by  an  enemy, 
or  devoured  by  a  beast  (in  which  case,  however,  a  man  was 
bound  to  restore  to  the  owner  whatever  was  left  of  the 
animal  thus  slain) :  whereas  in  the  other  cases  mentioned 
above,  he  was  not  bound  to  make  restitution;  but  only  to 
take  an  oath  in  order  to  clear  himself  of  suspicion.  Secondly, 
the  goods  deposited  might  be  lost  through  an  avoidable 
cause,  for  instance  by  theft:  and  then  the  depositary  was 
bound  to  restitution  on  account  of  his  neglect.  But,  as 
stated  above  [ad  4),  he  who  held  an  animal  on  loan,  was 
bound  to  restitution,  even  if  he  were  absent  when  it  de- 
preciated or  died:  because  he  was  held  responsible  for  less 
negligence  than  a  depositary,  who  was  only  held  responsible 
in  case  of  theft. 

Reply  Ohj.  6.  Workmen  who  offer  their  labour  for  hire, 
are  poor  men  who  toil  for  their  daily  bread:  and  therefore 
the  Law  commanded  wisely  that  they  should  be  paid  at  once, 
lest  they  should  lack  food.  But  they  who  offer  other  com- 
modities for  hire,  are  wont  to  be  rich:  nor  are  they  in  such 
need  of  their  price  in  order  to  gain  a  livelihood :  and  conse- 
quently the  comparison  does  not  hold. 


263  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS    Q.  105.  Art.  ± 

Reply  Ohj.  7.  The  purpose  for  which  judges  are  appointed 
among  men,  is  that  they  may  decide  doubtful  points  in 
matters  of  justice.  Now  a  matter  may  be  doubtful  in  two 
ways.  First,  among  simple-minded  people :  and  in  order  to 
remove  doubts  of  this  kind,  it  was  prescribed  (Deut.  xvi.  18) 
that  judges  mid  magistrates  should  be  appointed  in  each 
tribe,  to  judge  the  people  with  just  judgment. — Secondly,  a 
matter  may  be  doubtful  even  among  experts:  and  there- 
fore, in  order  to  remove  doubts  of  this  kind,  the  Law  pre- 
scribed that  all  should  foregather  in  some  chief  place  chosen 
by  God,  where  there  would  be  both  the  High-Priest,  who 
would  decide  doubtful  matters  relating  to  the  ceremonies 
of  divine  worship;  and  the  chief  judge  of  the  people,  who 
would  decide  matters  relating  to  the  judgments  of  men:  just 
as  even  now  cases  are  taken  from  a  lower  to  a  higher  court 
either  by  appeal  or  by  consultation.  Hence  it  is  written 
(Deut.  xvii.  8,  9) :  //  thou  perceive  that  there  he  among  you  a 
hard  and  doubtful  matter  in  judgment,  .  .  .  and  thou  see  that 
the  words  of  the  judges  within  thy  gates  do  vary  ;  arise  and 
go  up  to  the  place,  which  the  Lord  thy  God  shall  choose;  and 
thou  shall  come  to  the  priests  of  the  Levitical  race,  and  to  the 
judge  that  shall  he  at  that  time.  But  suchlike  doubtful  matters 
did  not  often  occur  for  judgment:  wherefore  the  people  were 
not  burdened  on  this  account. 

Reply  Ohj.  8.  In  the  business  affairs  of  men,  there  is  no 
such  thing  as  demonstrative  and  infallible  proof,  and  we 
must  be  content  with  a  certain  conjectural  probability, 
such  as  that  which  an  orator  employs  to  persuade.  Con- 
sequently, although  it  is  quite  possible  for  two  or  three 
witnesses  to  agree  to  a  falsehood,  yet  it  is  neither  easy  nor 
probable  that  they  succeed  in  so  doing :  wherefore  their  testi- 
mony is  taken  as  being  true,  especially  if  they  do  not  waver 
in  giving  it,  or  are  not  otherwise  suspect.  Moreover,  in 
order  that  witnesses  might  not  easily  depart  from  the  truth, 
the  Law  commanded  that  they  should  be  most  carefully 
examined,  and  that  those  who  were  found  untruthful  should 
be  severely  punished,  as  stated  in  Deut.  xix.  16,  seqq. 

There  was,  however,  a  reason  for  fixing  on  this  particular 


(}.  I05.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  264 

number,  in  token  of  the  unerring  truth  of  the  Divine  Persons, 
Who  are  sometimes  mentioned  as  two,  because  the  Holy 
Ghost  is  the  bond  of  the  other  two  Persons ;  and  sometimes 
as  three:  as  Augustine  observes  on  John  viii.  17:  In  your 
law  it  is  written  that  the  testimony  of  two  men  is  true. 

Reply  Ohj.  g.  A  severe  punishment  is  inflicted  not  only 
on  account  of  the  gravity  of  a  fault,  but  also  for  other 
reasons.  First,  on  account  of  the  greatness  of  the  sin, 
because  a  greater  sin,  other  things  being  equal,  deserves  a 
greater  punishment.  Secondly,  on  account  of  a  habitual 
sin,  since  men  are  not  easily  cured  of  habitual  sin  except  by 
severe  punishments.  Thirdly,  on  account  of  a  great  desire 
for  or  a  great  pleasure  in  the  sin:  for  men  are  not  easily 
deterred  from  such  sins  unless  they  be  severely  punished. 
Fourthly,  on  account  of  the  facility  of  committing  a  sin 
and  of  concealing  it:  for  suchlike  sins,  when  discovered, 
should  be  more  severely  punished  in  order  to  deter  others 
from  committing  them. 

Again,  with  regard  to  the  greatness  of  a  sin,  four  degrees 
may  be  observed,  even  in  respect  of  one  single  deed.  The 
first  is  when  a  sin  is  committed  unwillingly;  because  then, 
if  the  sin  be  altogether  involuntary,  man  is  altogether 
excused  from  punishment;  for  it  is  written  (Deut.  xxii.  25, 
seqq.)  that  a  damsel  who  suffers  violence  in  a  field  is  not 
guilty  of  death,  because  she  cried,  and  there  was  no  man 
to  help  her.  But  if  a  man  sinned  in  any  way  voluntarily, 
and  yet  through  weakness,  as  for  instance  when  a  man  sins 
from  passion,  the  sin  is  diminished:  and  the  pimishment, 
according  to  true  judgment,  should  be  diminished  also; 
unless  perchance  the  common  weal  requires  that  the  sin  be 
severely  punished  in  order  to  deter  others  from  committing 
such  sins,  as  stated  above. — The  second  degree  is  when  a 
man  sins  through  ignorance:  and  then  he  was  held  to  be 
guilty  to  a  certain  extent,  on  account  of  his  negligence  in 
acquiring  knowledge:  yet  he  was  not  punished  by  the  judges 
but  expiated  his  sin  by  sacrifices.  Hence  it  is  written 
(Lev.  iv.  2) :  The  soul  that  sinneth  through  ignorance,  etc. 
This  is,  however,  to  be  taken  as  applying  to  ignorance  of 


265  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS    Q.  105.  Art.  2 

fact;  and  not  to  ignorance  of  the  Divine  precept,  which  all 
were  bound  to  know.  —  The  third  degree  was  when  a 
man  sinned  from  pride,  i.e.,  through  deliberate  choice  or 
malice:  and  then  he  was  punished  according  to  the  great- 
ness of  the  sin.* — The  fourth  degree  was  when  a  man 
sinned  from  stubbornness  or  obstinacy:  and  then  he  was 
to  be  utterly  cut  off  as  a  rebel  and  a  destroyer  of  the  com- 
mandment of  the  Law.t 

Accordingly  we  must  say  that,  in  appointing  the  punish- 
ment for  theft,  the  Law  considered  what  would  be  likely 
to  happen  most  frequently  (Exod.  xxii.  1-9) :  wherefore,  as 
regards   theft   of  other  things  which  can   easily  be  safe- 
guarded from  a  thief,  the  thief  restored  only  twice  their 
value.     But  sheep  cannot  be   easily  safeguarded  from   a 
thief,  because  they  graze  in  the  fields:  wherefore  it  hap- 
pened more  frequently  that  sheep  were  stolen  in  the  fields. 
Consequently   the    Law   inflicted    a   heavier    penalty,    by 
ordering  four  sheep  to  be  restored  for  the  theft  of  one.     As 
to  cattle,  they  were  yet  more  difficult  to  safeguard,  because 
the}^  are  kept  in  the  fields,  and  do  not  graze  in  flocks  as 
sheep  do ;  wherefore  a  yet  more  heavy  penalty  was  inflicted 
in  their  regard,  so  that  five  oxen  were  to  be  restored  for 
one   ox.      And   this   I   say,   imless   perchance   the   animal 
itself  were  discovered  in  the  thief's  possession:  because  in 
that  case  he  had  to  restore  only  twice  the  number,  as  in  the 
case  of  other  thefts:  for  there  was  reason  to  presume  that 
he  intended  to  restore  the  animal,  since  he  kept  it  alive. — 
Again,  we  might  say,  according  to  a   gloss,  that  a  cow  is 
useful  in  five  ways  :  it  may  be  used  for  sacrifice,  for  ploughing, 
for  food,  for  milk,  and  its  hide  is  employed  for  various  pur- 
poses :  and  therefore  for  one  cow  five  had  to  be  restored. 
But  the  sheep  was  useful  in   four  ways:  for  sacrifice,  for 
meat,  for  milk,  and  for  Us  wool. — ^The  unruly  son  was  slain, 
not  because  he  ate  and  drank:  but  on  account  of  his  stub- 
bornness and  rebellion,  which  was  always  punished  by  death, 
as  stated  above. — As  to  the  man  who  gathered  sticks  on 
the  sabbath,  he  was  stoned  as  a  breaker  of  the  Law,  w^hich 
*  Cf.  Deut.  XXV.  2.  t  0/-  Num.  xv.  30,  31. 


Q.  105.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  266 

commanded  the  sabbath  to  be  observed,  to  testify  the 
belief  in  the  newness  of  the  world,  as  stated  above  (Q.  C, 
A.  5) :  wherefore  he  was  slain  as  an  unbeliever. 

Reply  Ohj.  10.  The  Old  Law  inflicted  the  death  penalty 
for  the  more  grievous  crimes,  viz.,  for  those  which  are  com- 
mitted against  God,  and  for  murder,  for  stealing  a  man, 
irreverence  towards  one's  parents,  adultery  and  incest. 
In  the  case  of  theft  of  other  things  it  inflicted  punishment 
by  indemnification:  while  in  the  case  of  blows  and  mutila- 
tion it  authorized  punishment  by  retaliation;  and  likewise 
for  the  sin  of  bearing  false  witness.  In  other  faults  of  less 
degree  it  prescribed  the  punishment  of  stripes  or  of  public 
disgrace. 

The  punishment  of  slavery  was  prescribed  by  the  Law 
in  two  cases.  First,  in  the  case  of  a  slave  who  was  un- 
willing to  avail  himself  of  the  privilege  granted  by  the  Law, 
whereby  he  was  free  to  depart  in  the  seventh  year  of  re- 
mission: wherefore  he  was  punished  by  remaining  a  slave 
for  ever. — Secondly,  in  the  case  of  a  thief,  who  had  not 
wherewith  to  make  restitution,  as  stated  in  Exod.  xxii.  3. 

The  punishment  of  absolute  exile  was  not  prescribed  by 
the  Law:  because  God  was  worshipped  by  that  people 
alone,  whereas  all  other  nations  were  given  to  idolatry: 
wherefore  if  any  man  were  exiled  from  that  people  abso- 
lutely, he  would  be  in  danger  of  falling  into  idolatry.  For 
this  reason  it  is  related  (i  Kings  xxvi.  19)  that  David  said 
to  Saul :  They  are  cursed  in  the  sight  of  the  Lord,  who  have 
cast  me  out  this  day,  that  I  should  not  dwell  in  the  inheritance 
of  the  Lord,  saying  :  Go,  serve  strange  gods.  There  was, 
however,  a  restricted  sort  of  exile  :  for  it  is  written  in  Deut. 
xix.  4  [cf.  Num.  XXXV.  25)  that  he  that  striketh  (Vulg., — 
killeth)  his  neighbour  ignorantly,  and  is  proved  to  have  had 
no  hatred  against  him,  shall  flee  to  one  of  the  cities  of  refuge 
and  abide  there  until  the  death  of  the  high-priest.  For  then 
it  became  lawful  for  him  to  return  home,  because  when  the 
whole  people  thus  suffered  a  loss  they  forgot  their  private 
quarrels,  so  that  the  next  of  kin  of  the  slain  were  not  so 
eager  to  kill  the  slayer. 


267  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS    Q.  105.  Art.  2 

Reply  Obj.  11.  Dumb  animals  were  ordered  to  be  slain, 
not  on  account  of  any  fault  of  theirs;  but  as  a  punishment 
to  their  owners,  who  had  not  safeguarded  their  beasts  from 
these  offences.  Hence  the  owner  was  more  severely  punished 
if  his  ox  had  butted  anyone  yesterday  or  the  day  before  (in 
which  case  steps  might  have  been  taken  to  avoid  the  danger), 
than  if  it  had  taken  to  butting  suddenly. — Or  again,  the 
animal  was  slain  in  detestation  of  the  sin;  and  lest  men 
should  be  horrified  at  the  sight  thereof. 

Reply  Obj.  12.  The  literal  reason  for  this  commandment, 
as  Rabbi  Moses  declares  [Doctr.  Perplex,  iii.),  was  because 
the  slayer  was  frequently  from  the  nearest  city:  wherefore 
the  slaying  of  the  calf  was  a  means  of  investigating  the 
hidden  murder.  This  was  brought  about  in  three  ways. 
In  the  first  place  the  elders  of  the  city  swore  that  they  had 
taken  every  measure  for  safeguarding  the  roads.  Secondly, 
the  owner  of  the  heifer  was  indemnified  for  the  slaying  of 
his  beast,  and  if  the  murder  were  previously  discovered, 
the  beast  was  not  slain.  Thirdly,  the  place,  where  the 
heifer  was  slain,  remained  uncultivated.  Wherefore,  in 
order  to  avoid  this  twofold  loss,  the  men  of  that  city  would 
readily  make  known  the  murderer,  if  they  knew  who  he  was: 
and  it  would  seldom  happen  but  that  some  word  or  sign 
would  escape  about  the  matter. — Or  again,  this  was  done 
in  order  to  frighten  people,  in  detestation  of  murder. 
Because  the  slaying  of  a  heifer,  which  is  a  useful  animal 
and  full  of  strength,  especially  before  it  has  been  put 
under  the  yoke,  signified  that  whoever  committed  murder, 
however  useful  and  strong  he  might  be,  was  to  forfeit  his 
life;  and  that,  by  a  cruel  death,  which  was  implied  by  the 
striking  off  of  its  head ;  and  that  the  murderer,  as  vile  and 
abject,  was  to  be  cut  off  from  the  fellowship  of  men,  which 
was  betokened  by  the  fact  that  the  heifer  after  being  slain 
was  left  to  rot  in  a  rough  and  uncultivated  place. 

Mystically,  the  heifer  taken  from  the  herd  signifies  the 
flesh  of  Christ;  which  had  not  drawn  a  yoke,  since  it  had 
done  no  sin;  nor  did  it  plough  the  ground,  i.e.,  it  never 
knew  the  stain  of  revolt.     The  fact  of  the  heifer  being  killed 


Q.  105.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  268 

in  an  uncultivated  valley  signified  the  despised  death  of 
Christ,  whereby  all  sins  are  washed  away,  and  the  devil  is 
shown  to  be  the  arch-murderer. 


Third  Article. 

whether  the  judicial  precepts  regarding  foreigners 
were  framed  in  a  suitable  manner  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  judicial  precepts  regarding 
foreigners  were  not  suitably  framed.  For  Peter  said  (Acts 
X.  34,  35) :  In  very  deed  I  perceive  that  God  is  not  a  respecter 
of  persons,  but  in  every  nation,  he  that  feareth  Him  and 
worketh  justice  is  acceptable  to  Him.  But  those  who  are 
acceptable  to  God  should  not  be  excluded  from  the  Church 
of  God.  Therefore  it  is  unsuitably  commanded  (Deut. 
xxiii.  3)  that  the  Ammonite  and  the  Moabite,  even  after  the 
tenth  generation,  shall  not  enter  into  the  church  of  the  Lord 
for  ever  :  whereas,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  prescribed  [ibid.  7) 
to  be  observed  with  regard  to  certain  other  nations:  Thou 
shall  not  abhor  the  Edomite,  because  he  is  thy  brother  ;  nor  the 
Egyptian  because  thou  wast  a  stranger  in  his  land. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  we  do  not  deserve  to  be  punished  for 
those  things  which  are  not  in  our  power.  But  it  is  not  in 
a  man's  power  to  be  an  eunuch,  or  born  of  a  prostitute. 
Therefore  it  is  unsuitably  commanded  (Deut.  xxiii.  i,  2) 
that  an  eunuch  and  one  born  of  a  prostitute  shall  not  enter 
into  the  church  of  the  Lord. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Old  Law  mercifully  forbade  strangers 
to  be  molested:  for  it  is  written  (Exod.  xxii.  21) :  Thou  shall 
not  molest  a  stranger,  nor  afflict  him  ;  for  yourselves  also  were 
strangers  in  the  land  of  Egypt :  and  (xxiii.  9) :  Thou  shall  not 
molest  a  stranger,  for  you  know  the  hearts  of  strangers,  for 
you  also  were  strangers  in  the  land  of  Egypt.  But  it  is  an 
affliction  to  be  burdened  with  usury.  Therefore  the  Law 
unsuitably  permitted  them  (Deut.  xxiii.  19,  20)  to  lend 
money  to  the  stranger  for  usury. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  men    are   much  more  akin  to  us  than 


269  THE  JUDICIAL  PRFXEPTS    Q.  105  Art.  3 

trees.  But  we  should  show  greater  care  and  love  for  these 
things  that  are  nearest  to  us,  according  to  Ecclus.  xiii.  19: 
Every  beast  loveth  its  like  :  so  also  every  man  him  that  is 
nearest  to  himself.  Therefore  the  Lord  unsuitably  com- 
manded (Deut.  XX.  13-19)  that  all  the  inhabitants  of  a 
captured  hostile  city  were  to  be  slain,  but  that  the  fruit- 
trees  should  not  be  cut  down. 

Ohj.  5.  Further,  every  one  should  prefer  the  common  good 
of  virtue  to  the  good  of  the  individual.  But  the  common 
good  is  sought  in  a  war  which  men  fight  against  their 
enemies.  Therefore  it  is  unsuitably  commanded  (Deut. 
XX.  5-7)  that  certain  men  should  be  sent  home,  for  instance 
a  man  that  had  built  a  new  house,  or  who  had  planted  a 
vineyard,  or  who  had  married  a  wife. 

Ohj.  6.  Further,  no  man  should  profit  by  his  own  fault. 
But  it  is  a  man's  fault  if  he  be  timid  or  faint-hearted: 
since  this  is  contrary  to  the  virtue  of  fortitude.  Therefore 
the  timid  and  faint-hearted  are  unfittingly  excused  from 
the  toil  of  battle  (Deut.  xx.  8). 

On  the  contrary,  Divine  Wisdom  declares  (Prov.  viii.  8): 
All  my  words  are  just,  there  is  nothing  wicked  nor  perverse 
in  them. 

I  answer  that,  Man's  relations  with  foreigners  are  two- 
fold: peaceful,  and  hostile:  and  in  directing  both  kinds  of 
relation  the  Law  contained  suitable  precepts.  For  the 
Jews  were  offered  three  opportunities  of  peaceful  relations 
with  foreigners.  First,  when  foreigners  passed  through 
their  land  as  travellers. — Secondly,  when  they  came  to  dwell 
in  their  land  as  new-comers.  And  in  both  these  respects  the 
Law  made  kind  provision  in  its  precepts:  for  it  is  written 
(Exod.  xxii.  21) :  Thou  shall  not  molest  a  stranger  [advenam)  ; 
and  again  [ibid,  xxiii.  9) :  Thou  shall  not  molest  a  stranger 
(peregrino) . — Thirdly,  when  any  foreigners  wished  to  be 
admitted  entirely  to  their  fellowship  and  mode  of  worship. 
With  regard  to  these  a  certain  order  was  observed.  For 
they  were  not  at  once  admitted  to  citizenship:  just  as  it 
was  the  law  with  some  nations  that  no  one  was  deemed 
a    citizen   except    after  two    or  three  generations,   as  [the 


Q.  105.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  270 

Philosopher  says  [Polit.  hi.).  The  reason  for  this  was  that 
if  foreigners  were  allowed  to  meddle  with  the  affairs  of  a 
nation  as  soon  as  they  settled  down  in  its  midst,  many 
dangers  might  occur,  since  the  foreigners  not  yet  having 
the  common  good  firmly  at  heart  might  attempt  something 
hurtful  to  the  people.  Hence  it  was  that  the  Law  prescribed 
in  respect  of  certain  nations  that  had  close  relations  with 
the  Jews  (viz.,  the  Egyptians  among  whom  they  were  bom 
and  educated,  and  the  Idumeans,  the  children  of  Esau, 
Jacob's  brother),  that  they  should  be  admitted  to  the  fellow- 
ship of  the  people  after  the  third  generation ;  whereas  others 
(with  whom  their  relations  had  been  hostile,  such  as  the 
Ammonites  and  Moabites)  were  never  to  be  admitted  to 
citizenship;  while  the  Amalekites,  who  were  yet  more 
hostile  to  them,  and  had  no  fellowship  of  kindred  with  them, 
were  to  be  held  as  foes  in  perpetuity:  for  it  is  written  (Exod. 
xvii.  16):  The  war  of  the  Lord  shall  he  against  Amalec  from 
generation  to  generation. 

In  like  manner  with  regard  to  hostile  relations  with 
foreigners,  the  Law  contained  suitable  precepts.  For,  in 
the  first  place,  it  commanded  that  war  should  be  declared 
for  a  just  cause:  thus  it  is  commanded  (Deut.  xx.  10)  that 
when  they  advanced  to  besiege  a  city,  they  should  at  first 
make  an  offer  of  peace. — Secondly,  it  enjoined  that  when 
once  they  had  entered  on  a  war  they  should  undauntedly 
persevere  in  it,  putting  their  trust  in  God.  And  in  order 
that  they  might  be  the  more  heedful  of  this  command,  it 
ordered  that  on  the  approach  of  battle  the  priest  should 
hearten  them  by  promising  them  God's  aid. — Thirdly,  it 
prescribed  the  removal  of  whatever  might  prove  an  obstacle 
to  the  fight,  and  that  certain  men,  who  might  be  in  the  way, 
should  be  sent  home. — Fourthly,  it  enjoined  that  they  should 
use  moderation  in  pursuing  the  advantage  of  victory,  by 
sparing  women  and  children,  and  by  not  cutting  down  the 
fruit-trees  of  that  country. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  Law  excluded  the  men  of  no  nation 
from  the  worship  of  God  and  from  things  pertaining  to  the 
welfare  of  the  soul:  for  it  is  written  (Exod.  xii.  48) :   //  any 


271  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  105.  Art.  3 

stranger  be  willing  to  dwell  among  you,  and  to  keep  the  Phase 
of  the  Lord  ;  all  his  males  shall  first  he  circumcised,  and  then 
shall  he  celebrate  it  according  to  the  manner,  and  he  shall  be 
as  that  which  is  horn  in  the  land.  But  in  temporal  matters 
concerning  the  public  life  of  the  people,  admission  was  not 
granted  to  everyone  at  once,  for  the  reason  given  above: 
but  to  some,  i.e.,  the  Egyptians  and  Idumeans,  in  the  third 
generation;  while  others  were  excluded  in  perpetuity,  in 
detestation  of  their  past  offence,  i.e.,  the  peoples  of  Moab, 
Ammon,  and  Amalec.  For  just  as  one  man  is  punished  for 
a  sin  committed  by  him,  in  order  that  others  seeing  this 
may  be  deterred  and  refrain  from  sinning;  so  too  may  one 
nation  or  city  be  punished  for  a  crime,  that  others  may 
refrain  from  similar  crimes. 

Nevertheless  it  was  possible  by  dispensation  for  a  man 
to  be  admitted  to  citizenship  on  account  of  some  act  of 
virtue:  thus  it  is  related  (Judith  xiv.  6)  that  Achior,  the 
captain  of  the  children  of  Ammon,  was  joined  to  the  people 
of  Israel,  with  all  the  succession  of  his  kindred. — ^The  same 
applies  to  Ruth  the  Moabite,  who  was  a  virtuous  woman 
(Ruth  iii.  11) :  although  it  may  be  said  that  this  prohibition 
regarded  men  and  not  women,  who  are  not  competent  to 
be  citizens  absolutely  speaking. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Polit.  iii.),  a  man 
is  said  to  be  a  citizen  in  two  ways:  first,  simply;  secondly, 
in  a  restricted  sense.  A  man  is  a  citizen  simply  if  he  has 
all  the  rights  of  citizenship,  for  instance,  the  right  of  debating 
or  voting  in  the  popular  assembly.  On  the  other  hand,  any 
man  may  be  called  citizen,  only  in  a  restricted  sense,  if  he 
dwells  within  the  state,  even  common  people  or  children 
or  old  men,  who  are  not  fit  to  enjoy  power  in  matters  per- 
taining to  the  common  weal.  For  this  reason  bastards,  by 
reason  of  their  base  origin,  were  excluded  from  the  ecclesia, 
i.e.,  from  the  popular  assembly,  down  to  the  tenth  generation. 
The  same  applies  to  eunuchs,  who  were  not  competent  to 
receive  the  honour  due  to  a  father,  especially  among  the 
Jews,  where  the  divine  worship  was  continued  through 
carnal  generation :  for  even  among  the  heathens,  those  who 


Q.  105.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  272 

had  many  children  were  marked  with  special  honour,  as  the 
Philosopher  remarks  [Polit.  ii.). — Nevertheless,  in  matters 
pertaining  to  the  grace  of  God,  eunuchs  were  not  discrimin- 
ated from  others,  as  neither  were  strangers,  as  already 
stated:  for  it  is  written  (Isa.  Ivi.  3):  Let  not  the  son  of  the 
stranger  that  adhereth  to  the  Lord  speak,  saying  :  The  Lord 
will  divide  and  separate  me  from  His  people.  And  let  not 
the  eunuch  say  :  Behold  I  am  a  dry  tree. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  It  was  not  the  intention  of  the  Law  to 
sanction  the  acceptance  of  usury  from  strangers,  but  only 
to  tolerate  it  on  account  of  the  proneness  of  the  Jews  to 
avarice ;  and  in  order  to  promote  an  amicable  feeling  towards 
those  out  of  whom  they  made  a  profit. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  A  distinction  was  observed  with  regard  to 
hostile  cities.  For  some  of  them  were  far  distant,  and  were 
not  among  those  which  had  been  promised  to  them.  When 
they  had  taken  these  cities,  they  killed  all  the  men  who  had 
fought  against  God's  people;  whereas  the  women  and 
children  were  spared.  But  in  the  neighbouring  cities  which 
had  been  promised  to  them,  all  were  ordered  to  be  slain, 
on  account  of  their  former  crimes,  to  punish  which  God 
sent  the  Israelites  as  executor  of  Divine  justice:  for  it  is 
written  (Deut.  ix.  5) :  Because  they  have  done  wickedly,  they 
are  destroyed  at  thy  coming  in. — ^The  fruit-trees  were  com- 
manded to  be  left  untouched,  for  the  use  of  the  people 
themselves,  to  whom  the  city  with  its  territory  was  destined 
to  be  subjected. 

Reply  Ohj.  5.  The  builder  of  a  new  house,  the  planter  of 
a  vineyard,  the  newly  married  husband,  were  excluded  from 
fighting,  for  two  reasons.  First,  because  man  is  wont  to 
give  all  his  affection  to  those  things  which  he  has  lately 
acquired,  or  is  on  the  point  of  having,  and  consequently  he 
is  apt  to  dread  the  loss  of  these  above  other  things.  Where- 
fore it  was  likely  enough  that  on  account  of  this  affection 
they  would  fear  death  all  the  more,  and  be  so  much  the 
less  brave  in  battle. — Secondly,  because,  as  the  Philos- 
opher says  (Phys.  ii.),  it  is  a  misfortune  for  a  man  if  he  is 
prevented  from  ohtaining  something  good  when  it  is  within  his 


273  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS    Q.  105.  Art.  4 

grasp.  And  so  lest  the  surviving  relations  should  be  the 
more  grieved  at  the  death  of  these  men  who  had  not  entered 
into  the  possession  of  the  good  things  prepared  for  them; 
and  also  lest  the  people  should  be  horror-stricken  at  the 
sight  of  their  misfortune:  these  men  were  taken  away  from 
the  danger  of  death  by  being  removed  from  the  battle. 

Reply  Ohj.  6.  The  timid  were  sent  back  home,  not  that 
they  might  be  the  gainers  thereby;  but  lest  the  people  might 
be  the  losers  by  their  presence,  since  their  timidity  and  flight 
might  cause  others  to  be  afraid  and  run  away. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  old  law  set  forth  suitable  precepts 
about  the  members  of  the  household  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  Old  Law  set  forth  un- 
suitable precepts  about  the  members  of  the  household.  For 
a  slave  is  in  every  respect  his  master's  property,  as  the 
Philosopher  states  {Polit.  i.).  But  that  which  is  a  man's 
property  should  be  his  always.  Therefore  it  was  imfitting 
for  the  Law  to  command  (Exod.  xxi.  2)  that  slaves  should 
go  out  free  in  the  seventh  year. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  a  slave  is  his  master's  property,  just  as  an 
animal,  e.g.,  an  ass  or  an  ox.  But  it  is  commanded  (Deut. 
xxii.  1-3)  with  regard  to  animals,  that  they  should  be 
brought  back  to  the  owner  if  they  be  found  going  astray. 
Therefore  it  was  unsuitably  commanded  (Deut.  xxiii.  15): 
Thou  shall  not  deliver  to  his  master  the  servant  that  is  fled  to  thee. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Divine  Law  should  encourage  mercy 
more  even  than  the  human  law.  But  according  to  human 
laws  those  who  illtreat  their  servants  and  maidservants  are 
severely  punished :  and  the  worse  treatment  of  all  seems  to  be 
that  which  results  in  death.  Therefore  it  is  unfittingly 
commanded  (Exod.  xxi.  20,  21)  that  he  that  striketh  his 
bondman  or  bondwoman  with  a  rod,  and  they  die  under  his 
hands  .  .  .  if  the  party  remain  alive  a  day  .  .  .  he  shall  not  be 
subject  to  the  punishment,  because  it  is  his  money. 

11.3  18 


o.  105.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  274 

Obj.  4.  Further,  the  dominion  of  a  master  over  his  slave 
differs  from  that  of  the  father  over  his  son  [Polit.  i.,  iii.). 
But  the  dominion  of  master  over  slave  gives  the  former  the 
right  to  sell  his  slave  or  maidservant.  Therefore  it  was 
unfitting  for  the  Law  to  allow  a  man  to  sell  his  daughter  to 
be  a  servant  or  handmaid  (Exod.  xxi.  7). 

Obj.  5.  Further,  a  father  has  power  over  his  son.  But 
he  who  has  power  over  the  sinner  has  the  right  to  punish 
him  for  his  offences.  Therefore  it  is  unfittingly  commanded 
(Deut.  xxi.  18  seqq.)  that  a  father  should  bring  his  son  to 
the  ancients  of  the  city  for  punishment. 

Obj.  6.  Further,  the  Lord  forbade  them  (Deut.  vii.  3,  seqq.) 
to  make  marriages  with  strange  nations;  and  commanded 
the  dissolution  of  such  as  had  been  contracted  (i  Esdras  x.) . 
Therefore  it  was  unfitting  to  allow  them  to  marry  captive 
women  from  strange  nations  (Deut.  xxi.  10  seqq.) 

Obj.  7.  Further,  the  Lord  forbade  them  to  marry  within 
certain  degrees  of  consanguinity  and  affinity,  according  to 
Levit.  xviii.  Therefore  it  was  unsuitably  commanded 
(Deut.  XXV.  5)  that  if  any  man  died  without  issue,  his  brother 
should  marry  his  wife. 

Obj.  8.  Further,  as  there  is  the  greatest  familiarity 
between  man  and  wife,  so  should  there  be  the  staunchest 
fidelity.  But  this  is  impossible  if  the  marriage  bond  can 
be  sundered.  Therefore  it  was  imfitting  for  the  Lord  to 
allow  (Deut.  xxiv.  1-4)  a  man  to  put  his  wife  away,  by  writing 
a  bill  of  divorce;  and  besides,  that  he  could  not  take  her 
again  to  wife. 

Obj.  9.  Further,  just  as  a  wife  can  be  faithless  to  her 
husband,  so  can  a  slave  be  to  his  master,  and  a  son  to  his 
father.  But  the  Law  did  not  command  any  sacrifice  to  be 
offered  in  order  to  investigate  the  injury  done  by  a  servant 
to  his  master,  or  by  a  son  to  his  father.  Therefore  it  seems 
to  have  been  superfluous  for  the  Law  to  prescribe  the 
sacrifice  of  jealousy  in  order  to  investigate  a  wife's  adultery 
(Num.  V.  12  seqq.).  Consequently  it  seems  that  the  Law 
put  forth  unsuitable  judicial  precepts  about  the  members 
of  the  household. 


275  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS    o.  105.  Art.  4 

Oil  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  xviii.  10) :  The  judgments 
of  the  Lord  are  true,  justified  in  themselves. 

I  answer  that.  The  mutual  relations  of  the  members  of  a 
household  regard  e very-day  actions  directed  to  the  neces- 
sities of  life,  as  the  Philosopher  states  {Polit.  i.).     Now  the 
preservation  of  man's  life  may  be  considered  from   two 
points  of  view.     First,  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  indi- 
vidual, i.e.,  in  so  far  as  man  preserves  his  individuality: 
and  for  the  purpose  of  the  preservation  of  life,  considered 
from  this  standpoint,  man  has  at  his  service  external  goods, 
by  means   of   which   he   provides  himself  with  food   and 
clothing  and  other  such  necessaries  of  life:  in  the  handling 
of  which  he  has  need  of  servants.     Secondly,  man's  life  is 
preserved  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  species,  by  means  of 
generation,  for  which  purpose  man  needs  a  wife,  that  she 
may  bear  him  children.     Accordingly  the  mutual  relations 
of  the  members  of  a  household  admit  of  a  threefold  combina- 
tion: viz.,  those  of  master  and  servant,  those  of  husband 
and  wife,  and  those  of  father  and  son :  and  in  respect  of  all 
these  relationships  the  Old  Law  contained  fitting  precepts. 
Thus,  with  regard  to  servants,  it  commanded  them  to  be 
treated  with  moderation, — both  as  to  their  work,  lest,  to 
wit,  they  should  be  burdened  with  excessive  labour,  where- 
fore the  Lord  commanded  (Deut.  v.  14)  that  on  the  Sabbath 
day  thy  manservant  and  thy  maidservant  should  rest  even  as 
thyself : — and  also  as  to  the  infliction  of  punishment,  for  it 
ordered  those  who  maimed  their  servants,  to  set  them  free 
(Exod.  xxi.  26,  27).     Similar  provision  was  made  in  favour 
of  a  maidservant  when  married  to  anyone  (ibid.  7,  scqq.). 
Moreover,  with  regard  to  those  servants  in  particular  who 
were  taken  from  among  the  (Hebrew)  people,  the  Law  pre- 
scribed that  they  should  go  out  free  in  the  seventh  year 
taking  whatever  they  brought  with  them,  even  their  clothes 
(ibid.  2,  scqq.) :  and  furthermore  it  was  commanded  (Deut. 
XV.  13)  that  they  should  be  given  provision  for  the  journey. 

With  regard  to  wives  the  Law  made  certain  prescriptions 
as  to  those  who  were  to  be  taken  in  marriage:  for  instance, 
that  they  should  marry  a  wife  from  their  own  tribe  (Num. 


Q.  105.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  276 

xxxvi.  6) :  and  this  lest  confusion  should  ensue  in  the 
property  of  various  tribes.  Also  that  a  man  should  marry 
the  wife  of  his  deceased  brother  when  the  latter  died  without 
issue,  as  prescribed  in  Deut.  xxv.  5,  6:  and  this  in  order  that 
he  who  could  not  have  successors  according  to  carnal 
origin,  might  at  least  have  them  by  a  kind  of  adoption,  and 
that  thus  the  deceased  might  not  be  entirely  forgotten. 
It  also  forbade  them  to  marry  certain  women ;  to  wit,  women 
of  strange  nations,  through  fear  of  their  losing  their  faith; 
and  those  of  their  near  kindred,  on  account  of  the  natural 
respect  due  to  them. — Furthermore  it  prescribed  in  what 
way  wives  were  to  be  treated  after  marriage.  To  wit,  that 
they  should  not  be  slandered  without  grave  reason:  where- 
fore it  ordered  punishment  to  be  inflicted  on  the  man  who 
falsely  accused  his  wife  of  a  crime  (Deut.  xxii.  13,  seqq.). 
Also  that  a  man's  hatred  of  his  wife  should  not  be  detri- 
mental to  his  son  (Deut.  xxi.  15,  seqq.).  Again,  that  a  man 
should  not  ill-use  his  wife  through  hatred  of  her,  but  rather 
that  he  should  write  a  bill  of  divorce  and  send  her  away 
(Deut.  xxiv.  i).  Furthermore,  in  order  to  foster  conjugal 
love  from  the  very  outset,  it  was  prescribed  that  no  public 
duties  should  be  laid  on  a  recently  married  man,  so  that  he 
might  be  free  to  rejoice  with  his  wife. 

With  regard  to  children,  the  Law  commanded  parents  to 
educate  them  by  instructing  them  in  the  faith:  hence  it  is 
written  (Exod.  xii.  26  seqq.) :  When  your  children  shall  say  to 
you  :  What  is  the  meaning  of  this  service  ?  you  shall  say  to 
them  :  It  is  the  victim  of  the  passage  of  the  Lord.  Moreover, 
they  are  commanded  to  teach  them  the  rules  of  right  con- 
duct: wherefore  it  is  written  (Deut.  xxi.  20)  that  the  parents 
had  to  say:  He  slighteth  hearing  our  admonitions,  he  giveth 
himself  to  revelling  and  to  debauchery. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  As  the  children  of  Israel  had  been  delivered 
by  the  Lord  from  slavery,  and  for  this  reason  were  bound 
to  the  service  of  God,  He  did  not  wish  them  to  be  slaves  in 
perpetuity.  Hence  it  is  written  (Lev.  xxv.  39,  seqq.):  If 
thy  brother,  constrained  by  poverty,  sell  himself  to  thee,  thou 
shall  not  oppress  him  with  the  service  of  bondservants :  but  he 


277  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  105.  Art.  4 

shall  he  as  a  hireling  and  a  sojourner  .  .  .  for  they  are  My 
servants,  and  I  brought  them  out  of  the  land  of  Egypt :  let  them 
not  he  sold  as  hondmen  :  and  consequently,  since  they  were 
slaves,  not  absolutely  but  in  a  restricted  sense,  after  a  lapse 
of  time  they  were  set  free. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  This  commandment  is  to  be  understood  as 
referring  to  a  servant  whom  his  master  seeks  to  kill,  or  to 
help  him  in  committing  some  sin. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  With  regard  to  the  ill-treatment  of  servants, 
the  Law  seems  to  have  taken  into  consideration  whether  it 
was  certain  or  not :  since  if  it  were  certain,  the  Law  fixed  a 
penalty:  for  maiming,  the  penalty  was  forfeiture  of  the  ser- 
vant, who  was  ordered  to  be  given  his  liberty:  while  for  slay- 
ing, the  punishment  was  that  of  a  murderer,  when  the  servant 
died  under  the  blow  of  his  master. — If,  however,  the  hurt 
were  not  certain,  but  only  probable,  the  Law  did  not  impose 
any  penalty  as  regards  a  man's  own  servant:  for  instance  if 
the  servant  did  not  die  at  once  after  being  struck,  but  after 
some  days:  for  it  would  be  uncertain  whether  he  died  as  a 
result  of  the  blows  he  received.  For  when  a  man  struck  a 
free  man,  yet  so  that  he  did  not  die  at  once,  but  walked 
ahroad  again  upon  his  staff,  he  that  struck  him  was  quit  of 
murder,  even  though  afterwards  he  died.  Nevertheless  he 
was  bound  to  pay  the  doctor's  fees  incurred  by  the  victim 
of  his  assault.  But  this  was  not  the  case  if  a  man  killed  his 
own  servant:  because  whatever  the  servant  had,  even  his 
very  person,  was  the  property  of  his  master.  Hence  the 
reason  for  his  not  being  subject  to  a  pecuniary  penalty  is  set 
down  as  being  because  it  is  his  money. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  As  stated  above  {ad  i),  no  Jew  could  own 
a  Jew  as  a  slave  absolutely:  but  only  in  a  restricted  sense, 
as  a  hireling  for  a  fixed  time.  And  in  this  way  the  Law 
permitted  that  through  stress  of  poverty  a  man  might  sell 
his  son  or  daughter.  This  is  shown  by  the  very  words  of  the 
Law,  where  we  read:  //  any  man  sell  his  daughter  to  he  a 
servant,  she  shall  not  go  out  as  bondwomen  are  wont  to  go  out. 
Moreover,  in  this  way  a  man  might  sell  not  only  his  son,  but 
even  himself,  rather  as  a  hireling  than  as  a  slave,  according 


Q.  105.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  278 

to  Lev.  XXV.  39,  40 :  //  thy  brother,  constrained  by  poverty,  sell 
himself  to  thee,  thou  shalt  not  oppress  him  with  the  service  of 
bondservants  :  but  he  shall  be  as  a  hireling  and  a  sojourner. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  As  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  x.),  the 
paternal  authority  has  the  power  only  of  admonition;  but 
not  that  of  coercion,  whereby  rebellious  and  headstrong 
persons  can  be  compelled.  Hence  in  this  case  the  Lord 
commanded  the  stubborn  son  to  be  punished  by  the  rulers 
of  the  city. 

Reply  Obj.  6.  The  Lord  forbade  them  to  marry  strange 
women  on  account  of  the  danger  of  seduction,  lest  they 
should  be  led  astray  into  idolatry.  And  specially  did  this 
prohibition  apply  with  respect  to  those  nations  who  dwelt 
near  them,  because  it  was  more  probable  that  they  would 
adopt  their  religious  practices.  When,  however,  the  woman 
was  willing  to  renounce  idolatry  and  become  an  adherent 
of  the  Law,  it  was  lawful  to  take  her  in  marriage:  as  was  the 
case  with  Ruth  whom  Booz  married.  Wherefore  she  said 
to  her  mother-in-law  (Ruth  i.  16) :  Thy  people  shall  be  my 
people,  and  thy  God  my  God.  Accordingly  it  was  not  per- 
mitted to  marry  a  captive  woman  unless  she  first  shaved 
her  hair,  and  pared  her  nails,  and  put  off  the  raiment  wherein 
she  was  taken,  and  mourned  for  her  father  and  mother,  in 
token  that  she  renounced  idolatry  for  ever. 

Reply  Obj.  7.  As  Chrysostom  says  [Horn,  xlviii.  super 
Matth.),  because  death  was  an  unmitigated  evil  for  the  Jews, 
who  did  everything  with  a  view  to  the  present  life,  it  was 
ordained  that  children  should  be  born  to  the  dead  man  through 
his  brother  :  thus  affording  a  certain  mitigation  to  his  death. 
It  was  not,  however,  ordained  that  any  other  than  his  brother  or 
one  next  of  kin  should  marry  the  wife  of  the  deceased,  because 
the  offspring  of  this  union  would  not  be  looked  upon  as  that  of 
the  deceased  :  and,  moreover,  a  stranger  would  not  be  under  the 
obligation  to  support  the  household  of  the  deceased,  as  his 
brother  would  be  bound  to  do  from  motives  of  justice  on  account 
of  his  relationship.  Hence  it  is  evident  that  in  marrying 
the  wife  of  his  dead  brother,  he  took  his  dead  brother's 
place. 


279  THE  JUDICIAL  PRECEPTS     Q.  105.  Art.  ., 

Reply  Obj.  8.  The  Law  permitted  a  wife  to  be  divorced, 
not  as  though  it  were  just  absolutely  speaking,  but  on  account 
of  the  Jews'  hardness  of  heart,  as  Our  Lord  declared  (Matth. 
xix.  8).  Of  this,  however,  we  must  speak  more  fully  in  the 
treatise  on  Matrimony  (SuppL,  Q.  LXVIL). 

Reply  Obj.  9.  Wives  break  their  conjugal  faith  by  adultery, 
both  easily,  for  motives  of  pleasure,  and  hiddcnly,  since  the 
eye  of  the  adulterer  observeth  darkness  (Job.  xxiv.  15).  But 
this  does  not  apply  to  a  son  in  respect  of  his  father,  or  to  a 
servant  in  respect  of  his  master:  because  the  latter  infidelity 
is  not  the  result  of  the  lust  of  pleasure,  but  rather  of  malice: 
nor  can  it  remain  hidden  like  the  infidelity  of  an  adulterous 
woman. 


QUESTION  CVI. 

OF  THE  LAW  OF  THE  GOSPEL,  CALLED  THE  NEW  LAW. 
CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

In  proper  sequence  we  have  to  consider  now  the  Law  of  the 
Gospel  which  is  called  the  New  Law:  and  in  the  first  place 
we  must  consider  it  in  itself ;  secondly,  in  comparison  with 
the  Old  Law;  thirdly,  we  shall  treat  of  those  things  that  are 
contained  in  the  New  Law.  Under  the  first  head  there  are 
four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  What  kind  of  law  is  it  ?  i.e.,  is  it 
a  written  law  or  is  it  instilled  in  the  heart  ?  (2)  Of  its 
efficacy,  i.e.,  does  it  justify  ?  (3)  Of  its  beginning: — should 
it  have  been  given  at  the  beginning  of  the  world  ?  (4)  Of 
its  end:  i.e.,  whether  it  will  last  until  the  end,  or  will  another 
law  take  its  place  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  the  new  law  is  a  written  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  is  a  written  law. 
For  the  New  Law  is  just  the  same  as  the  Gospel.  But  the 
Gospel  is  set  forth  in  writing,  according  to  John  xx.  31: 
But  these  are  written  that  you  may  believe.  Therefore  the 
New  Law  is  a  written  law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  law  that  is  instilled  in  the  heart  is 
the  natural  law,  according  to  Rom.  ii.  14,  15:  [The  Gentiles) 
do  by  nature  those  things  that  are  of  the  law  .  .  .  who  have 
(Vulg., — show)  the  work  of  the  law  written  in  their  hearts.  If 
therefore  the  law  of  the  Gospel  were  instilled  in  our  hearts, 
it  would  not  be  distinct  from  the  law  of  nature. 

280 


28i  THE  LAW  OF  THE  GOSPEL    Q.  106.  Art.  i 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  law  of  the  Gospel  is  proper  to  those 
who  are  in  the  state  of  the  New  Testament.  But  the  law 
that  is  instilled  in  the  heart  is  common  to  those  who  are  in 
the  New  Testament  and  to  those  who  are  in  the  Old  Testa- 
ment: for  it  is  written  (Wis.  vii.  27)  that  Divine  Wisdom 
throiigh  nations  conveyeth  herself  into  holy  souls,  she  makcth 
the  friends  of  God  and  ^prophets.  Therefore  the  New  Law  is 
not  instilled  in  our  hearts. 

On  the  contrary,  The  New  Law  is  the  law  of  the  New 
Testament.  But  the  law  of  the  New  Testament  is  instilled 
in  our  hearts.  For  the  Apostle,  quoting  the  authority  of 
Jeremias  xxxi.  31,  33:  Behold  the  days  shall  come,  saith  the 
Lord  ;  and  I  will  perfect  unto  the  house  of  Israel,  and  unto  the 
house  of  Juda,  a  new  testament,  says,  explaining  what  this 
testament  is  (Heb.  viii.  8,  10) :  For  this  is  the  testament  which 
I  will  make  to  the  house  of  Israel .  .  .by  giving  (Vulg., — I  will 
give)  Afy  laws  into  their  mind,  and  in  their  heart  will  I  write 
them.     Therefore  the  New  Law  is  instilled  in  our  hearts. 

I  answer  that.  Each  thing  appears  to  be  that  which  pre- 
ponderates in  it,  as  the  Philosopher  states  [Ethic,  ix.).  Now 
that  which  is  preponderant  in  the  law  of  the  New  Testament, 
and  whereon  all  its  efficacy  is  based,  is  the  grace  of  the  Holy 
Ghost,  which  is  given  through  faith  in  Christ.  Consequently 
the  New  Law  is  chiefly  the  grace  itself  of  the  Holy  Ghost, 
which  is  given  to  those  who  believe  in  Christ.  This  is  mani- 
festly stated  by  the  Apostle  who  says  (Rom.  iii.  27) :  Where 
is  .  .  .  thy  boasting  ?  It  is  excluded.  By  what  law  ?  Of 
works  ?  No,  but  by  the  law  of  faith  :  for  he  calls  the  grace 
itself  of  faith  a  law.  And  still  more  clearly  it  is  written 
(Rom.  viii.  2) :  The  law  of  the  spirit  of  life,  in  Christ  Jesus, 
hath  delivered  me  from  the  laiv  of  sin  and  of  death.  Hence 
Augustine  says  [De  Spir.  et  Lit.  xxiv.)  that  as  the  law  of 
deeds  was  written  on  tables  of  stone,  so  is  the  law  of  faith 
inscribed  on  the  hearts  of  the  faithfiil  :  and  elsewhere,  in  the 
same  book  [ibid,  xxi.):  What  else  are  the  Divine  laws  written 
by  God  Himself  on  our  hearts,  but  the  very  presence  of  His 
Holy  Spirit  ? 

Nevertheless  the  New  Law  contains  certain  things  that 


Q.  io6.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  282 

dispose  us  to  receive  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  and  per- 
taining to  the  use  of  that  grace :  such  things  are  of  secondary 
importance,  so  to  speak,  in  the  New  Law;  and  the  faithful 
needed  to  be  instructed  concerning  them,  both  by  word  and 
writing,  both  as  to  what  they  should  believe  and  as  to  what 
they  should  do.  Consequently  we  must  say  that  the  New 
Law  is  in  the  first  place  a  law  that  is  inscribed  on  our  hearts, 
but  that  secondarily  it  is  a  written  law. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  Gospel  writings  contain  only  such  things 
as  pertain  to  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  either  by  disposing 
us  thereto,  or  by  directing  us  to  the  use  thereof.  Thus 
with  regard  to  the  intellect,  the  Gospel  contains  certain 
matters  pertaining  to  the  manifestation  of  Christ's  Godhead 
or  humanity,  which  dispose  us  by  means  of  faith  through 
which  we  receive  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost:  and  with 
regard  to  the  affections,  it  contains  matters  touching  the 
contempt  of  the  world,  whereby  man  is  rendered  fit  to 
receive  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost:  for  the  world,  i.e., 
worldly  men,  cannot  receive  the  Holy  Ghost  (John  xiv.  17). 
As  to  the  use  of  spiritual  grace,  this  consists  in  works  of 
virtue  to  which  the  writings  of  the  New  Testament  exhort 
men  in  divers  ways. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  There  are  two  ways  in  which  a  thing  may  be 
instilled  into  man.  First,  through  being  part  of  his  nature, 
and  thus  the  natural  law  is  instilled  into  man.  Secondly, 
a  thing  is  instilled  into  man  by  being,  as  it  were,  added  on 
to  his  nature  by  a  gift  of  grace.  In  this  way  the  New  Law 
is  instilled  into  man,  not  only  by  indicating  to  him  what  he 
should  do,  but  also  by  helping  him  to  accomplish  it. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  No  man  ever  had  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost 
except  through  faith  in  Christ  either  explicit  or  implicit: 
and  by  faith  in  Christ  man  belongs  to  the  New  Testament. 
Consequently  whoever  had  the  law  of  grace  instilled  into 
them  belonged  to  the  New  Testament. 


283  THE  LAW  OF  THE  GOSPEL    Q.  ioG.  Art.  2 

Second  Article, 
whether  the  new  law  justifies  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seco7id  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  does  not  justify. 
For  no  man  is  justified  unless  he  obey  God's  law,  according 
to  Heb.  V.  9.  He,  i.e.,  Christ,  became  to  all  that  obey  Him 
the  cause  of  eternal  salvation.  But  the  Gospel  does  not 
always  cause  men  to  believe  in  it:  for  it  is  written  (Rom. 
X.  16):  All  do  not  obey  the  Gospel.  Therefore  the  New  Law 
does  not  justify. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Apostle  proves  in  his  epistle  to  the 
Romans  that  the  Old  Law  did  not  justify,  because  trans- 
gression increased  at  its  advent:  for  it  is  stated  (Rom. 
iv.  15) :  The  Law  worketh  wrath  :  for  where  there  is  no  law, 
neither  is  there  transgression.  But  much  more  did  the 
New  Law  increase  transgression:  since  he  who  sins  after 
the  giving  of  the  New  Law  deserves  greater  punishment, 
according  to  Heb.  x.  28,  29 :  A  man  making  void  the  Law  of 
Moses  dieth  without  any  mercy  under  two  or  three  witnesses. 
How  much  more,  do  you  think,  he  deserveth  worse  punishments, 
who  hath  trodden  under-foot  the  Son  of  God,  etc.  ?  Therefore 
the  New  Law,  like  the  Old  Law,  does  not  justify. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  justification  is  an  effect  proper  to  God, 
according  to  Rom.  viii.  33:  God  that  justifieth.  But  the 
Old  Law  was  from  God  just  as  the  New  Law.  Therefore 
the  New  Law  does  not  justify  any  more  than  the  Old  Law. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  i.  16) :  /  am  not 
ashamed  of  the  Gospel :  for  it  is  the  power  of  God  unto  salvation 
to  everyone  that  believeth.  But  there  is  no  salvation  but  to 
those  who  are  justified.  Therefore  the  Law  of  the  Gospel 
justifies. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  there  is  a  twofold 
element  in  the  Law  of  the  Gospel.  There  is  the  chief  element, 
viz.,  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost  bestowed  inwardly.  And 
as  to  this,  the  New  Law  justifies.  Hence  Augustine  says 
(De  Spir.  et  Lit.  xvii.) :  There,  i.e.,  in  the  Old  Testament, 
the  Law  was  set  forth  in  an  outward  fashion,  that  the  ungodly 


Q.  io6.  Ari.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  284 

might  he  afraid ;  here,  i.e.,  in  the  New  Testament,  it  is  given 
in  an  inward  manner,  that  they  may  he  justified. — ^The  other 
element  of  the  Evangelical  Law  is  secondary:  namely,  the 
teachings  of  faith,  and  those  commandments  which  direct 
human  affections  and  human  actions.  And  as  to  this,  the 
New  Law  does  not  justify.  Hence  the  Apostle  says  (2  Cor. 
iii.  6) :  The  letter  killeth,  hut  the  spirit  quickeneth  :  and  Augus- 
tine explains  this  (De  Spir.  et  Lit.  xiv.,  xvii.)  by  saying  that 
the  letter  denotes  any  writing  that  is  external  to  man,  even 
that  of  the  moral  precepts  such  as  are  contained  in  the 
Gospel.  Wherefore  the  letter,  even  of  the  Gospel  would 
kill,  imless  there  were  the  inward  presence  of  the  healing 
grace  of  faith. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  argument  is  true  of  the  New  Law,  not 
as  to  its  principal,  but  as  to  its  secondary  element:  i.e.,  as  to 
the  dogmas  and  precepts  outwardly  put  before  man  either  in 
words  or  in  writing. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  the  grace  of  the  New  Testament 
helps  man  to  avoid  sin,  yet  it  does  not  so  confirm  man  in 
good  that  he  cannot  sin:  for  this  belongs  to  the  state  of 
glory.  Hence  if  a  man  sin  after  receiving  the  grace  of  the 
New  Testament,  he  deserves  greater  punishment,  as  being 
ungrateful  for  greater  benefits,  and  as  not  using  the  help 
given  to  him.  And  this  is  why  the  New  Law  is  not  said  to 
work  wrath  :  because  as  far  as  it  is  concerned  it  gives  man 
sufficient  help  to  avoid  sin. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  same  God  gave  both  the  New  and  the 
Old  Law,  but  in  different  ways.  For  He  gave  the  Old  Law 
written  on  tables  of  stone:  whereas  He  gave  the  New  Law 
written  in  the  fleshly  tahles  of  the  heart,  as  the  Apostle 
expresses  it  (2  Cor.  iii.  3).  Wherefore,  as  Augustine  says 
[De  Spir.  et  Lit.  xviii.),  the  Apostle  calls  this  letter  which  is 
written  outside  man,  a  ministration  of  death  and  a  ministration 
of  condemnation  :  whereas  he  calls  the  other  letter,  i.e.,  the  Law 
of  the  New  Testament,  the  ministration  of  the  spirit  and  the 
ministration  of  justice  :  hecause  through  the  gift  of  the  Spirit 
we  work  justice,  and  are  delivered  from  the  condemnation  due 
to  transgression. 


285  THE  LAW  OF  THE  GOSPEL    o.  loO.  Art.  3 

TiiiKD  Article. 

WHETHER    THE    NEW    LAW   SHOULD    HAVE    BEEN    GIVEN 
FROM    THE    BEGINNING   OF   THE   WORLD  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  should  have  been 
given  from  the  beginning  of  the  world.  For  there  is  no 
respect  of  persons  with  God  (Rom.  ii.  11).  But  all  men  have 
sinned  and  do  need  the  glory  of  God  (ibid.  iii.  23).  Therefore 
the  Law  of  the  Gospel  should  have  been  given  from  the 
beginning  of  the  world,  in  order  that  it  might  bring  succour 
to  all. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  as  men  dwell  in  various  places,  so  do  they 
live  in  various  times.  But  God,  Who  will  have  all  men  to 
be  saved  (i  Tim.  ii.  4),  commanded  the  Gospel  to  be  preached 
in  all  places,  as  may  be  seen  in  the  last  chapters  of  Matthew 
and  Mark.  Therefore  the  Law  of  the  Gospel  should  have 
been  at  hand  for  all  times,  so  as  to  be  given  from  the  begin- 
ning of  the  world . 

Obj.  3.  Further,  man  needs  to  save  his  soul,  which  is  for 
all  eternity,  more  than  to  save  his  body,  which  is  a  temporal 
matter.  But  God  provided  man  from  the  beginning  of  the 
world  with  things  that  are  necessary  for  the  health  of  his 
body,  by  subjecting  to  his  power  whatever  was  created  for 
the  sake  of  man  (Gen.  i.  26-29).  Therefore  the  New  Law 
also,  which  is  very  necessary  for  the  health  of  the  soul,  should 
have  been  given  to  man  from  the  beginning  of  the  world. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  xv.  46) :  That  was 
not  first  which  is  spiritual,  but  that  which  is  natural.  But 
the  New  Law  is  highly  spiritual.  Therefore  it  was  not 
fitting  for  it  to  be  given  from  the  beginning  of  the  world. 

/  answer  that,  Three  reasons  may  be  assigned  why  it  was 
not  fitting  for  the  New  Law  to  be  given  from  the  beginning 
of  the  world.  The  first  is  because  the  New  Law,  as  stated 
above  (A.  i),  consists  chiefly  in  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost: 
which  it  behoved  not  to  be  given  abundantly  until  sin, 
which  is  an  obstacle  to  grace,  had  been  cast  out  of  man 
through  the  accomplishment  of  his  redemption  by  Christ: 


Q.  106.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA/THEOLOGICA  "  286 

wherefore  it  is  written  (John  vii.  39):  As  yet  the  Spirit  was 
not  given,  because  Jesus  was  not  yet  glorified.  This  reason 
the  Apostle  states  clearly  (Rom.  viii.  2,  seqq.)  where,  after 
speaking  of  the  Law  of  the  Spirit  of  life,  he  adds:  God  sending 
His  own  Son,  in  the  likeness  of  sinful  flesh,  of  sin*  hath  con- 
demned sin  in  the  flesh,  that  the  justification  of  the  Law  might 
he  fulfilled  in  us. 

A  second  reason  may  be  taken  from  the  perfection  of  the 
New  Law.  Because  a  thing  is  not  brought  to  perfection  at 
once  from  the  outset,  but  through  an  orderly  succession  of 
time;  thus  one  is  at  first  a  boy,  and  then  a  man.  And  this 
reason  is  stated  by  the  Apostle  (Gal.  iii.  24,  25) :  The  Law 
was  our  pedagogue  in  Christ  that  we  might  he  justified  hy 
faith.  But  after  the  faith  is  come,  we  are  no  longer  under  a 
pedagogue. 

The  third  reason  is  found  in  the  fact  that  the  New  Law 
is  the  law  of  grace:  wherefore  it  behoved  man  first  of  all 
to  be  left  to  himself  under  the  state  of  the  Old  Law,  so  that 
through  falling  into  sin,  he  might  realize  his  weakness,  and 
acknowledge  his  need  of  grace.  This  reason  is  set  down  by 
the  Apostle  (Rom.  v.  20) :  The  Law  entered  in,  that  sin  might 
abound  :  and  when  sin  abounded  grace  did  more  abound. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Mankind  on  accoimt  of  the  sin  of  our  first 
parents  deserved  to  be  deprived  of  the  aid  of  grace :  and  so 
from  whom  it  is  withheld  it  is  justly  withheld,  and  to  whom  it 
is  given,  it  is  mercifully  given,  as  Augustine  states  in  his  book 
on  the  perfection  of  justice  {cf  Epist.  ccvii.).  Consequently 
it  does  not  follow  that  there  is  respect  of  persons  with  God, 
from  the  fact  that  He  did  not  offer  the  Law  of  grace  to  all 
from  the  beginning  of  the  world,  which  Law  was  to  be 
published  in  due  course  of  time,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  state  of  mankind  does  not  vary  accord- 
ing to  diversity  of  place,  but  according  to  succession  of 
time.     Hence  the  New  Law  avails  for  all  places,  but  not 

*  S.  Thomas,  quoting  perhaps  from  memory,  omits  the  et  [and), 
after  sinful  flesh.  The  text  quoted  should  read  thus, — in  the  likeness 
of  sinful  flesh,  and  a  sin  offering  [nepl  afxaprlas) ,  hath,  etc. 


I 


28;  THE  LAW  OF  THE  GOSPEL    Q.  loo.  Am.  4 

for  all  times:  although  at  all  times  there  have  been  some 
persons  belonging  to  the  New  Testament,  as  stated  above 
(A.  I  ad  3). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Things  pertaining  to  the  health  of  the  body 
are  of  service  to  man  as  regards  his  nature,  which  sin  does 
not  destroy:  whereas  things  pertaining  to  the  health  of  the 
soul  are  ordained  to  grace,  which  is  forfeit  through  sin. 
Consequently  the  comparison  will  not  hold. 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  new  law  will  last  till  the  end  of 

the  world  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  will  not  last  till 
the  end  of  the  world.  Because,  as  the  Apostle  says  (i  Cor. 
xiii.  10),  when  that  which  is  perfect  is  come,  that  which  is  in 
part  shall  be  done  away.  But  the  New  Law  is  in  part,  since 
the  Apostle  says  {ibid.  9) :  We  know  in  part  and  we  prophesy 
in  part.  Therefore  the  New  Law  is  to  be  done  away,  and 
will  be  succeeded  by  a  more  perfect  state. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Our  Lord  (John  xvi.  13)  promised  His 
disciples  the  knowledge  of  all  truth  when  the  Holy  Ghost, 
the  Comforter,  should  come.  But  the  Church  knows  not  yet 
all  truth  in  the  state  of  the  New  Testament.  Therefore  we 
must  look  forward  to  another  state,  wherein  all  truth  will 
be  revealed  by  the  Holy  Ghost. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  just  as  the  Father  is  distinct  from  the  Son 
and  the  Son  from  the  Father,  so  is  the  Holy  Ghost  distinct 
from  the  Father  and  the  Son.  But  there  was  a  state  corre- 
sponding with  the  Person  of  the  Father,  viz.,  the  state  of  the 
Old  Law,  wherein  men  were  intent  on  begetting  children: 
and  likewise  there  is  a  state  corresponding  to  the  Person  of 
the  Son:  viz.,  the  state  of  the  New  Law,  wherein  the  clergy 
who  are  intent  on  wisdom  (which  is  appropriated  to  the  Son) 
hold  a  prominent  place.  Therefore  there  will  be  a  third 
state  corresponding  to  the  Holy  Ghost,  wherein  spiritual 
men  will  hold  the  first  place. 


Q.  io6.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  288 

Obj.  4.  Eurthcr,  Our  Lord  said  (Matth.  xxiv.  14) :  This 
Gospel  of  the  kingdom  shall  he  preached  in  the  whole  world  .  .  . 
and  then  shall  the  consummation  come.  But  the  Gospel  of 
Christ  is  already  preached  throughout  the  whole  world :  and 
yet  the  consummation  has  not  yet  come.  Therefore  the 
Gospel  of  Christ  is  not  the  Gospel  of  the  kingdom,  but 
another  Gospel,  that  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  is  to  come  yet,  like 
unto  another  Law. 

On  the  contrary,  Our  Lord  said  (Matth.  xxiv.  34) :  /  say  to 
you  that  this  generation  shall  not  pass  till  all  [these)  things  be 
done  :  which  passage  Chrysostom  (Hom.  Ixxvii.)  explains  as 
referring  to  the  generation  of  those  that  believe  in  Christ. 
Therefore  the  state  of  those  who  believe  in  Christ  will  last 
until  the  consummation  of  the  world. 

/  answer  that,  The  state  of  the  world  may  change  in  two 
ways.  In  one  way,  according  to  a  change  of  law:  and  thus 
no  other  state  will  succeed  this  state  of  the  New  Law. 
Because  the  state  of  the  New  Law  succeeded  the  state  of  the 
Old  Law,  as  a  more  perfect  law  a  less  perfect  one.  Now  no 
state  of  the  present  life  can  be  more  perfect  than  the  state 
of  the  New  Law:  since  nothing  can  approach  nearer  to  the 
last  end  than  that  which  is  the  immediate  cause  of  our 
being  brought  to  the  last  end.  But  the  New  Law  does  this : 
wherefore  the  Apostle  says  (Heb.  x.  19-22) :  Having  there- 
fore, brethren,  a  confidence  in  the  entering  into  the  Holies  by 
the  blood  of  Christ,  a  new  .  .  .  way  which  He  hath  dedicated 
for  us  .  .  .  let  us  draw  near.  Therefore  no  state  of  the  present 
life  can  be  more  perfect  than  that  of  the  New  Law,  since  the 
nearer  a  thing  is  to  the  last  end  the  more  perfect  it  is. 

In  another  way  the  state  of  mankind  may  change  according 
as  man  stands  in  relation  to  one  and  the  same  law  more  or 
less  perfectly.  And  thus  the  state  of  the  Old  Law  under- 
went frequent  changes,  since  at  times  the  laws  were  very 
well  kept,  and  at  other  times  were  altogether  unheeded. 
Thus,  too,  the  state  of  the  New  Law  is  subject  to  change 
with  regard  to  various  places^  times,  and  persons,  according 
as  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost  dwells  in  man  more  or  less 
perfectly.     Nevertheless  we  are  not  to  look  forward  to  a 


28q  THE  LAW  OF  THE  GOSPEL    Q.  ior).ART.4 

state  wherein  man  is  to  possess  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost 
more  perfectly  than  he  has  possessed  it  hitherto,  especially 
the  apostles  who  received  the  firstfruits  of  the  Spirit,  i.e., 
sooner  and  more  abundantly  than  others,  as  a  gloss  expounds 
on  Rom.  viii.  23. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  Dionysius  says  [Eccl.  Hier.  v.),  there 
is  a  threefold  state  of  mankind ;  the  first  was  under  the  Old 
Law;  the  second  is  that  of  the  New  Law;  the  third  will  take 
place  not  in  this  life,  but  in  heaven.  But  as  the  first 
state  is  figurative  and  imperfect  in  comparison  with  the 
state  of  the  Gospel;  so  is  the  present  state  figurative  and 
imperfect  in  comparison  with  the  heavenly  state,  with  the 
advent  of  which  the  present  state  will  be  done  away  as 
expressed  in  that  very  passage  [verse  12) :  We  see  now  through 
a  glass  in  a  dark  manner  ;  hut  then  face  to  face. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  As  Augustine  says  [Contra  Faust,  xix.), 
Montanus  and  Priscilla  pretended  that  Our  Lord's  promise 
to  give  the  Holy  Ghost  was  fulfilled,  not  in  the  apostles,  but 
in  themselves.  In  like  manner  the  Manicheans  maintained 
that  it  was  fulfilled  in  Manes  whom  they  held  to  be  the 
Paraclete.  Hence  none  of  the  above  received  the  Acts  of 
the  Apostles,  where  it  is  clearly  shown  that  the  aforesaid 
promise  was  fulfilled  in  the  apostles:  just  as  Our  Lord 
promised  them  a  second  time  (Acts  i.  5) :  You  shall  he  bap- 
tized with  the  Holy  Ghost,  not  many  days  hence  :  which  we 
read  as  having  been  fulfilled  in  Acts  ii.  However,  these 
foolish  notions  are  refuted  by  the  statement  (John  vii.  39) 
that  as  yet  the  Spirit  was  not  given,  because  Jesus  was  not  yet 
glorified ;  from  which  we  gather  that  the  Holy  Ghost  was 
given  as  soon  as  Christ  was  glorified  in  His  Resurrection  and 
Ascension.  Moreover,  this  puts  out  of  court  the  senseless 
idea  that  the  Holy  Ghost  is  to  be  expected  to  come  at  some 
other  time. 

Now  the  Holy  Ghost  taught  the  apostles  all  truth  in 
respect  of  matters  necessary  for  salvation;  those  things, 
to  wit,  that  we  are  bound  to  believe  and  to  do.  But  He 
did  not  teach  them  about  all  future  events :  for  this  did  not 
regard  them  according  to  Acts  i.  7:  It  is  not  for  you  to  know 

II.  3  19 


Q.  io6.  Art.  4      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  290 

the  times  or  moments  which  the  Father  hath  put  in  His  own 
power. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  Old  Law  corresponded  not  only  to  the 
Father,  but  also  to  the  Son :  because  Christ  was  foreshadowed 
in  the  Old  Law.  Hence  Our  Lord  said  (John  v.  46) :  //  you 
did  believe  Moses,  you  would  perhaps  believe  Me  also  ;  for 
he  wrote  of  Me.  In  like  manner  the  New  Law  corresponds 
not  only  to  Christ,  but  also  to  the  Holy  Ghost ;  according  to 
Rom.  viii.  2:  The  law  of  the  Spirit  of  life  in  Christ  Jesus,  etc. 
Hence  we  are  not  to  look  forward  to  another  law  corre- 
sponding to  the  Holy  Ghost. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Since  Christ  said  at  the  very  outset  of  the 
preaching  of  the  Gospel :  The  kingdom  of  heaven  is  at  hand 
(Matth.  iv.  17),  it  is  most  absurd  to  say  that  the  Gospel  of 
Christ  is  not  the  Gospel  of  the  kingdom.  But  the  preaching 
of  the  Gospel  of  Christ  may  be  understood  in  two  ways. 
First,  as  denoting  the  spreading  abroad  of  the  knowledge 
of  Christ :  and  thus  the  Gospel  was  preached  throughout  the 
whole  world  even  at  the  time  of  the  apostles,  as  Chrysostom 
states  {Hom.  Ixxv.  in  Matth.).  And  in  this  sense  the  words 
that  follow, — and  then  shall  the  consummation  come,  refer  to 
the  destruction  of  Jerusalem,  of  which  He  was  speaking 
literally.- — Secondly,  the  preaching  of  the  Gospel  may  be 
understood  as  extending  throughout  the  world  and  pro- 
ducing its  full  effect,  so  that,  to  wit,  the  Church  would  be 
founded  in  every  nation.  And  in  this  sense,  as  Augustine 
writes  to  Hesychius  [Epist.  cxcix.),  the  Gospel  is  not 
preached  to  the  whole  world  yet,  but,  when  it  is,  the  con- 
summation of  the  world  will  come. 


QUESTION  CVII. 

OF  THE  NEW  LAW  AS  COMPARED  WITH  THE  OLD. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  New  Law  as  compared  with  the 
Old:  under  which  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  the  New  Law  is  distinct  from  the  Old  Law  ? 
(2)  Whether  the  New  Law  fulfils  the  Old  ?  (3)  Whether  the 
New  Law  is  contained  in  the  Old  ?  (4)  Which  is  the  more 
burdensome,  the  New  or  the  Old  Law  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  the  new  law  is  distinct  from  the  old  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  is  not  distinct 
from  the  Old.  Because  both  these  laws  were  given  to  those 
who  believe  in  God :  since  without  faith  it  is  impossible  to 
please  God,  according  to  Heb.  xi.  6.  But  the  faith  of  olden 
times  and  of  nowadays  is  the  same,  as  the  gloss  says  on 
Matth.  xxi.  9.     Therefore  the  law  is  the  same  also. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Augustine  says  (Contra  Adamant.  Manich. 
discip.)  that  the  difference  between  the  Law  and  Gospel  is 
small, "^ — fear  and  love  (timor  et  amor).  But  the  New  and 
Old  Laws  cannot  be  differentiated  in  respect  of  these  two 
things:  since  even  the  Old  Law  comprised  precepts  of 
charity:  Thou  shall  love  thy  neighbour  (Lev.  xix.  18),  and: 
Thou  shall  love  the  Lord  thy  God  (Deut.  vi.  5). — In  like 
manner  neither  can  they  differ  according  to  the  other 
difference   which    Augustine    assigns     [Contra   Faust,   iv.), 

*  Referring  to  the  Latin  words  timor  and  amor. 

291 


Q.  107.  Art.  r     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  292 

viz.,  that  the  Old  Testament  contained  temporal  promises, 
whereas  the  New  Testament  contains  spiritual  and  eternal 
promises  :  since  even  the  New  Testament  contains  tem- 
poral promises,  according  to  Mark  x.  30 :  He  shall  receive 
a  hundred  times  as  much  .  .  .  in  this  time,  houses  and  brethren, 
etc. :  while  in  the  Old  Testament  they  hoped  in  promises 
spiritual  and  eternal,  according  to  Heb.  xi.  16:  But  now  they 
desire  a  better,  that  is  to  say,  a  heavenly  country,  which  is  said 
of  the  patriarchs.  Therefore  it  seems  that  the  New  Law 
is  not  distinct  from  the  Old. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Apostle  seems  to  distinguish  both 
laws  by  calling  the  Old  Law  a  law  of  works,  and  the  New 
Law  a  law  of  faith  (Rom.  iii.  27).  But  the  Old  Law  was 
also  a  law  of  faith,  according  to  Heb.  xi.  39:  All  were  (Vulg., 
— All  these  being)  approved  by  the  testimony  of  faith,  which  he 
says  of  the  fathers  of  the  Old  Testament.  In  like  manner 
the  New  Law  is  a  law  of  works:  since  it  is  written  (Matth. 
V.  44) :  Do  good  to  them  that  hate  you  ;  and  (Luke  xxii.  19) : 
Do  this  for  a  commemoration  of  Me.  Therefore  the  New  Law 
is  not  distinct  from  the  Old. 

On  the  contrary,  the  Apostle  says  (Heb.  vii.  12) :  The 
priesthood  being  translated  it  is  necessary  that  a  translation 
also  be  made  of  the  Law.  But  the  priesthood  of  the  New 
Testament  is  distinct  from  that  of  the  Old,  as  the  Apostle 
shows  in  the  same  place.     Therefore  the  Law  is  also  distinct. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XC,  A.  2;  Q.  XCL, 
A.  4),  every  law  ordains  human  conduct  to  some  end. 
Now  things  ordained  to  an  end  may  be  divided  in  two  ways, 
considered  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  end.  First,  through 
being  ordained  to  different  ends:  and  this  difference  will  be 
specific,  especially  if  such  ends  are  proximate.  Secondly, 
by  reason  of  being  closely  or  remotely  connected  with  the 
end.  Thus  it  is  clear  that  movements  differ  in  species 
through  being  directed  to  different  terms:  while  according 
as  one  part  of  a  movement  is  nearer  to  the  term  than  another 
part,  the  difference  of  perfect  and  imperfect  movement  is 
assessed. 

Accordingly  then  two  laws  may  be  distinguished  from 


293     NEW  LAW  COMPARED  WITH  OLD     Q.  107.  Art.  i 

one  another  in  two  ways.  First,  through  being  altogether 
diverse,  from  the  fact  that  they  are  ordained  to  diverse 
ends:  thus  a  state-law  ordained  to  democratic  government, 
would  differ  specifically  from  a  law  ordained  to  government 
by  the  aristocracy.  Secondly,  two  laws  may  be  distinguished 
from  one  another,  through  one  of  them  being  more  closely 
connected  with  the  end,  and  the  other  more  remotely:  thus 
in  one  and  the  same  state  there  is  one  law  enjoined  on  men 
of  mature  age,  who  can  forthwith  accomplish  that  which 
pertains  to  the  common  good;  and  another  law  regulating 
the  education  of  children  who  need  to  be  taught  how  they 
are  to  achieve  manly  deeds  later  on. 

We  must  therefore  say  that,  according  to  the  first  way, 
the  New  Law  is  not  distinct  from  the  Old  Law:  because 
they  both  have  the  same  end,  namely,  man's  subjection  to 
God;  and  there  is  but  one  God  of  the  New  and  of  the  Old 
Testament,  according  to  Rom.  iii.  30:  It  is  one  God  that 
jiistificth  circurncision  by  faith,  and  uncircumcision  through 
faith. — According  to  the  second  way,  the  New  Law  is 
distinct  from  the  Old  Law:  because  the  Old  Law  is  like  a 
pedagogue  of  children,  as  the  Apostle  says  (Gal.  iii.  24), 
whereas  the  New  Law  is  the  law  of  perfection,  since  it  is  the 
law  of  charity,  of  which  the  Apostle  says  (Coloss.  iii.  14) 
that  it  is  the  bond  of  perfection. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  unity  of  faith  under  both  Testaments 
witnesses  to  the  unity  of  end:  for  it  has  been  stated  above 
(O.  LXIL,  A.  2)  that  the  object  of  the  theological  virtues, 
among  which  is  faith,  is  the  last  end.  Yet  faith  had  a 
different  state  in  the  Old  and  in  the  New  Law:  since  what 
they  believed  as  future,  we  believe  as  fact. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  All  the  differences  assigned  between  the  Old 
and  New  Laws  are  gathered  from  their  relative  perfection 
and  imperfection.  For  the  precepts  of  every  law  prescribe 
acts  of  virtue.  Now  the  imperfect,  who  as  yet  are  not  pos- 
sessed of  a  virtuous  habit,  are  directed  in  one  way  to  perform 
virtuous  acts,  while  those  w^ho  are  perfected  by  the  possession 
of  virtuous  habits  are  directed  in  another  way.  For  those 
who  as  yet  are  not  endowed  with  virtuous  habits,  are  directed 


Q.  107.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  294 

to  the  performance  of  virtuous  acts  by  reason  of  some  out- 
ward cause:  for  instance,  by  the  threat  of  punishment,  or  the 
promise  of  some  extrinsic  rewards,  such  as  honour,  riches, 
or  the  like.  Hence  the  Old  Law,  which  was  given  to  men 
who  were  imperfect,  that  is,  who  had  not  yet  received 
spiritual  grace,  was  called  the  law  of  fear,  inasmuch  as  it 
induced  men  to  observe  its  commandments  by  threatening 
them  with  penalties;  and  is  spoken  of  as  containing  tem- 
poral promises. — On  the  other  hand,  those  who  are  possessed 
of  virtue,  are  inchned  to  do  virtuous  deeds  through  love  of 
virtue,  not  on  account  of  some  extrinsic  punishment  or 
reward.  Hence  the  New  Law  which  derives  its  pre-eminence 
from  the  spiritual  grace  instilled  into  our  hearts,  is  called  the 
Law  of  love  :  and  it  is  described  as  containing  spiritual  and 
eternal  promises,  which  are  objects  of  the  virtues,  chiefly  of 
charity.  Accordingly  such  persons  are  inclined  of  themselves 
to  those  objects,  not  as  to  something  foreign  but  as  to  some- 
thing of  their  own. — For  this  reason,  too,  the  Old  Law  is 
described  as  restraining  the  hand,  not  the  will  (Peter  Lombard, 
— Sent,  iii.) ;  since  when  a  man  refrains  from  some  sins  through 
fear  of  being  punished,  his  will  does  not  shrink  simply  from 
sin,  as  does  the  will  of  a  man  who  refrains  from  sin  through 
love  of  righteousness  :  and  hence  the  New  Law,  which  is  the 
Law  of  love,  is  said  to  restrain  the  will. 

Nevertheless  there  were  some  in  the  state  of  the  Old 
Testament  who,  having  charity  and  the  grace  of  the  Holy 
Ghost,  looked  chiefly  to  spiritual  and  eternal  promises:  and 
in  this  respect  they  belonged  to  the  New  Law. — In  like 
manner  in  the  New  Testament  there  are  some  carnal  men 
who  have  not  yet  attained  to  the  perfection  of  the  New 
Law;  and  these  it  was  necessary,  even  under  the  New  Testa- 
ment, to  lead  to  virtuous  action  by  the  fear  of  punishment 
and  by  temporal  promises. 

But  although  the  Old  Law  contained  precepts  of  charity, 
nevertheless  it  did  not  confer  the  Holy  Ghost  by  Whom 
charity  .  .  .  is  spread  abroad  in  our  hearts  {Rom.  v.  5). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CVL,  AA.  i,  2),  the 
New  Law  is  called  the  law  of  faith,  in  so  far  as  its  pre- 


295      NEW  LAW  COMPARED  WITH  OLD     (J.  107.  Art.  z 

eminence  is  derived  from  that  very  grace  which  is  given 
inwardly  to  behevers,  and  for  this  reason  is  called  the  grace 
of  faith.  Nevertheless  it  consists  secondarily  in  certain 
deeds,  moral  and  sacramental:  but  the  New  Law  does  not 
consist  chiefly  in  these  latter  things,  as  did  the  Old  Law. 
As  to  those  mider  the  Old  Testament  who  through  faith 
were  acceptable  to  God,  in  this  respect  they  belonged  to  the 
New  Testament:  for  they  were  not  justified  except  through 
faith  in  Christ,  Who  is  the  Author  of  the  New  Testament. 
Hence  of  Moses  the  Apostle  says  (Heb.  xi.  26)  that  he 
esteemed  the  reproach  of  Christ  greater  riches  than  the  treasure 
of  the  Egyptians. 

Second  Article, 
whether  the  new  law  fulfils  the  old  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  does  not  fulfil 
the  Old.  Because  to  fulfil  and  to  void  are  contrary.  But 
the  New  Law  voids  or  excludes  the  observances  of  the  Old 
Law:  for  the  Apostle  says  (Gal.  v.  2) :  //  you  he  circumcised, 
Christ  shall  profit  you  nothing.  Therefore  the  New  Law  is 
not  a  fulfilment  of  the  Old. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  one  contrary  is  not  the  fulfilment  of 
another.  But  Our  Lord  propounded  in  the  New  Law 
precepts  that  were  contrary  to  precepts  of  the  Old  Law. 
For  we  read  (Matth.  v.  27-32) :  You  have  heard  that  it  was 
said  to  them  of  old:  .  .  .  Whosoever  shall  put  away  his  wifCy 
let  him  give  her  a  hill  of  divorce.  But  I  say  to  you  that  whoso- 
ever shall  put  away  his  wife  .  .  .  maketh  her  to  commit  adultery. 
Furthermore,  the  same  evidently  applies  to  the  prohibition 
against  swearing,  against  retaliation,  and  against  hating 
one's  enemies.  In  like  manner  Our  Lord  seems  to  have  done 
away  with  the  precepts  of  the  Old  Law  relating  to  the 
different  kinds  of  foods  (Matth.  xv.  11) :  Not  that  which  goeth 
into  the  mouth  defileth  a  man  :  hut  what  cometh  out  of  the  mouth, 
this  defileth  a  man.  Therefore  the  New  Law^  is  not  a  fulfil- 
ment of  the  Old. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  whoever  acts  against  a  law  does  not 


Q.  107.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  296 

fulfil  the  law.  But  Christ  in  certain  cases  acted  against 
the  Law.  For  He  touched  the  leper  (Matth.  viii.  3),  which 
was  contrary  to  the  Law.  Likewise  He  seems  to  have  fre- 
quently broken  the  sabbath;  since  the  Jews  used  to  say  of 
Him  (John  ix.  16) :  This  man  is  not  of  God,  who  keepeth  not 
the  sabbath.  Therefore  Christ  did  not  fulfil  the  Law :  and  so 
the  New  Law  given  by  Christ  is  not  a  fulfilment  of  the  Old. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  the  Old  Law  contained  precepts,  moral, 
ceremonial,  and  judicial,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCIX.,  A.  4). 
But  Our  Lord  (Matth.  v.)  fulfilled  the  Law  in  some  respects, 
but  without  mentioning  the  judicial  and  ceremonial  pre- 
cepts. Therefore  it  seems  that  the  New  Law  is  not  a  com- 
plete fulfilment  of  the  Old. 

On  the  contrary,  Our  Lord  said  (Matth.  v.  17) :  /  am  not 
come  to  destroy,  but  to  fulfil :  and  went  on  to  say  {verse  18) : 
One  jot  or  one  tittle  shall  not  pass  of  the  Law  till  all  be  ful- 
filled. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  the  New  Law  is 
compared  to  the  Old  as  the  perfect  to  the  imperfect.  Now 
everything  perfect  fulfils  that  which  is  lacking  in  the  im- 
perfect. And  accordingly  the  New  Law  fulfils  the  Old  by 
supplying  that  which  was  lacking  in  the  Old  Law. 

Now  two  things  in  the  Old  Law  offer  themselves  to  our 
consideration:  viz.,  the  end,  and  the  precepts  contained  in 
the  Law. 

Now  the  end  of  every  law  is  to  make  men  righteous  and 
virtuous,  as  was  stated  above  (Q.  XCIL,  A.  i):  and  conse- 
quently the  end  of  the  Old  Law  was  the  justification  of 
men.  The  Law,  however,  could  not  accomplish  this:  but 
foreshadowed  it  by  certain  ceremonial  actions,  and  promised 
it  in  words.  And  in  this  respect,  the  New  Law  fulfils  the 
Old  by  justifying  men  through  the  power  of  Christ's  Passion. 
This  is  what  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  viii.  3,  4):  What  the 
Law  could  not  do  .  .  .  God  sending  His  own  Son  in  the  like- 
ness of  sinful  fiesh  .  .  .  hath  condemned  sin  in  the  fiesh,  that 
the  justification  of  the  Law  might  be  fulfilled  in  us. — And  in 
this  respect,  the  New  Law  gives  what  the  Old  Law  promised, 
according  to  2  Cor.  i.  20:  Whatever  are  the  promises  of  God, 


297     NEW  LAW  COMPARED  W ITH  OLD    Q.  107.  Ak 


r.  2 


in  Him,  i.e.,  in  Christ,  they  are  '  y^«.'* — Again,  in  this 
respect,  it  also  fulfils  what  the  Old  Law  foreshadowed. 
Hence  it  is  written  (Coloss.  ii.  17)  concerning  the  ceremonial 
precepts  that  they  were  a  shadow  of  things  to  come,  hut  the 
body  is  of  Christ  :  in  other  words,  the  reality  is  found  in 
Christ.  Wherefore  the  New  Law  is  called  the  law  of  reality; 
whereas  the  Old  Law  is  called  the  law  of  shadow  or  of  figure. 

Now  Christ  fulfilled  the  precepts  of  the  Old  Law  both  in 
His  works  and  in  His  doctrine.  In  His  works,  because  He 
was  willing  to  be  circumcised  and  to  fulfil  the  other  legal 
observances,  which  were  binding  for  the  time  being;  accord- 
ing to  Gal.  iv.  4:  Made  under  the  Law. — In  His  doctrine  He 
fulfilled  the  precepts  of  the  Law  in  three  ways.  First,  by 
explaining  the  true  sense  of  the  Law.  This  is  clear  in  the 
case  of  murder  and  adultery,  the  prohibition  of  which  the 
Scribes  and  Pharisees  thought  to  refer  only  to  the  exterior 
act:  wherefore  Our  Lord  fulfilled  the  Law  by  showing  that 
the  prohibition  extended  also  to  the  interior  acts  of  sins. — 
Secondly,  Our  Lord  fulfilled  the  precepts  of  the  Law  by 
prescribing  the  safest  way  of  complying  with  the  statutes 
of  the  Old  Law.  Thus  the  Old  Law  forbade  perjury:  and 
this  is  more  safely  avoided,  by  abstaining  altogether  from 
swearing,  save  in  cases  of  urgency. — Thirdly,  Our  Lord  ful- 
filled the  precepts  of  the  Law,  by  adding  some  counsels  of 
perfection:  this  is  clearly  seen  in  Matth.  xix.  21  [of.  Mark 
X.  21 ;  Luke  xviii.  22)  where  Our  Lord  said  to  the  man  who 
affirmed  that  he  had  kept  all  the  precepts  of  the  Old  Law: 
One  thing  is  wanting  to  thee :  //  thou  wilt  he  perfect,  go,  sell 
whatsoever  thou  hast,  etc. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  New  Law  does  not  void  observance  of 
the  Old  Law  except  in  the  point  of  ceremonial  precepts,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  CIIL,  AA.  3,  4).  Now  the  latter  were 
figurative  of  something  to  come.  Wherefore  from  the  very 
fact  that  the  ceremonial  precepts  were  fulfilled  when  those 
things  were  accomplished  which  they  foreshadowed,  it 
follows  that  they  are  no  longer  to  be  observed:  for  if  they 

*  The  Doiuiy  version  reads   thus:  All  the  promises  of  God  are  in 
Him,  'It  is.' 


Q.  107.  Art.  2      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  298 

were  to  be  observed,  this  would  meaa  that  something  is 
still  to  be  accomplished  and  is  not  yet  fulfilled.  Thus  the 
promise  of  a  future  gift  holds  no  longer  when  it  has  been 
fulfilled  by  the  presentation  of  the  gift.  In  this  way  the 
legal  ceremonies  are  abolished  by  being  fulfilled. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  Augustine  says  (Contra  Faust,  xix.,) 
those  precepts  of  Our  Lord  are  not  contrary  to  the  precepts 
of  the  Old  Law.  For  what  Our  Lord  commanded  about  a 
man  not  putting  away  his  wife,  is  not  contrary  to  what  the 
Law  prescribed.  For  the  Law  did  not  say  :  '  Let  him  that 
wills,  put  his  wife  away  ':  the  contrary  of  which  would  be  not 
to  put  her  away.  On  the  contrary,  the  Law  was  unwilling  that 
a  man  should  put  away  his  wife,  since  it  prescribed  a  delay, 
so  that  excessive  eagerness  for  divorce  might  cease  through 
being  weakened  during  the  writing  of  the  bill.  Hence  Our 
Lord,  in  order  to  impress  the  fact  that  a  wife  oiight  not  easily 
to  be  put  away,  allowed  no  exception  save  in  the  case  of  fornica- 
tion. The  same  applies  to  the  prohibition  about  swearing, 
as  stated  above. — The  same  is  also  clear  with  respect  to  the 
prohibition  of  retaliation.  For  the  Law  fixed  a  limit  to 
revenge,  by  forbidding  men  to  seek  vengeance  unreason- 
ably: whereas  Our  Lord  deprived  them  of  vengeance  more 
completely  by  commanding  them  to  abstain  from  it  alto- 
gether.— With  regard  to  the  hatred  of  one's  enemies.  He 
dispelled  the  false  interpretation  of  the  Pharisees,  by  ad- 
monishing us  to  hate,  not  the  person,  but  his  sin. — As  to 
discriminating  between  various  foods,  which  was  a  cere- 
monial matter.  Our  Lord  did  not  forbid  this  to  be  observed : 
but  He  showed  that  no  foods  are  naturally  unclean,  but  only 
in  token  of  something  else,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CIL,  A.  6  ad  i). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  It  was  forbidden  by  the  Law  to  touch  a 
leper;  because  by  doing  so,  man  incurred  a  certain  unclean- 
ness  of  irregularity,  as  also  by  touching  the  dead,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  CIL,  A.  5  ad  ^.  But  Our  Lord,  Who  healed  the 
leper,  could  not  contract  an  uncleanness. — By  those  things 
which  He  did  on  the  sabbath.  He  did  not  break  the  sab- 
bath in  reality,  as  the  Master  Himself  shows  in  the  Gospel: 
both  because  He  worked  miracles  by  His  Divine  power, 


299     NEW  LAW  COMPAKIi:!)  WITH  OLD     o.  107.  Art.  1 

which  is  ever  active  among  things;  and  because  His  works 
were  concerned  with  the  salvation  of  man,  while  the  Phari- 
sees were  concerned  for  the  well-being  of  animals  even  on 
the  sabbath;  and  again  because  on  account  of  urgency  He 
excused  His  disciples  for  gathering  the  ears  of  corn  on  the 
sabbath.  But  He  did  seem  to  break  the  sabbath  according 
to  the  superstitious  interpretation  of  the  Pharisees,  who 
thought  that  man  ought  to  abstain  from  doing  even  works 
of  kindness  on  the  sabbath;  which  was  contrary  to  the 
intention  of  the  Law. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  The  reason  why  the  ceremonial  precepts  of 
the  Law  are  not  mentioned  in  Matth.  v.  is  because,  as  stated 
above  (ad  i),  their  observance  was  abolished  by  their  fulfil- 
ment.— But  of  the  judicial  precepts  He  mentioned  that  of 
retaliation:  so  that  what  He  said  about  it  should  refer  to 
all  the  others.  With  regard  to  this  precept.  He  taught  that 
the  intention  of  the  Law  was  that  retaliation  should  be 
sought  out  of  love  of  justice,  and  not  as  a  punishment  out 
of  revengeful  spite,  which  He  forbade,  admonishing  man 
to  be  ready  to  suffer  yet  greater  insults;  and  this  remains 
still  in  the  New  Law. 


Third  Article, 
whether  the  new  law  is  contained  in  the  old  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  is  not  contained 
in  the  Old.  Because  the  New  Law  consists  chiefly  in  faith : 
wherefore  it  is  called  the  law  of  faith  (Rom.  iii.  27).  But 
many  points  of  faith  are  set  forth  in  the  New  Law,  which 
are  not  contained  in  the  Old.  Therefore  the  New  Law  is 
not  contained  in  the  Old. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  a  gloss  says  on  Matth.  v.  19,  He  that 
shall  break  one  of  these  least  commandments,  that  the  lesser 
commandments  are  those  of  the  Law,  and  the  greater  com- 
mandments, those  contained  in  the  Gospel.  Now  the 
greater  cannot  be  contained  in  the  lesser.  Therefore  the 
New  Law  is  not  contained  in  the  Old. 


Q.  107.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  300 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  who  holds  the  container  holds  the  con- 
tents. If,  therefore,  the  New  Law  is  contained  in  the  Old, 
it  follows  that  whoever  had  the  Old  Law  had  the  New:  so 
that  it  was  superfluous  to  give  men  a  New  Law  when  once 
they  had  the  Old.  Therefore  the  New  Law  is  not  contained 
in  the  Old. 

On  the  contrary,  As  expressed  in  Ezech.  i.  16,  there  was 
a  wheel  in  the  midst  of  a  i&hcel,  i.e.,  the  New  Testament  within 
the  Old,  according  to  Gregory's  exposition. 

/  answer  that,  One  thing  may  be  contained  in  another  in 
two  ways.  First,  actually;  as  a  located  thing  is  in  a  place. 
Secondly,  virtually;  as  an  effect  in  its  cause,  or  as  the  com- 
plement in  that  which  is  incomplete;  thus  a  genus  contains 
its  species,  and  a  seed  contains  the  whole  tree,  virtually. 
It  is  in  this  way  that  the  New  Law  is  contained  in  the  Old: 
for  it  has  been  stated  (A.  i)  that  the  New  Law  is  compared 
to  the  Old  as  perfect  to  imperfect.  Hence  Chrysostom, 
expounding  Mark  iv.  28,  The  earth  of  itself  bringeth  forth 
fruit,  first  the  blade,  then  the  ear,  afterwards  the  full  corn  in 
the  ear,  expresses  himself  as  follows :  He  brought  forth  first 
the  blade,  i.e.,  the  Law  of  Nature  ;  then  the  ear,  i.e.,  the  Law 
of  Moses  ;  lastly,  the  full  corn,  i.e.,  the  Law  of  the  Gospel. 
Hence  then  the  New  Law  is  in  the  Old  as  the  corn  in  the 
ear. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Whatsoever  is  set  down  in  the  New  Testa- 
ment explicitly  and  openly  as  a  point  of  faith,  is  contained 
in  the  Old  Testament  as  a  matter  of  belief,  but  implicitly, 
under  a  figure.  And  accordingly,  even  as  to  those  things 
which  we  are  bound  to  believe,  the  New  Law  is  contained 
in  the  Old. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  precepts  of  the  New  Law  are  said  to 
be  greater  than  those  of  the  Old  Law,  in  the  point  of  their 
being  set  forth  explicitly.  But  as  to  the  substance  itself  of 
the  precepts  of  the  New  Testament,  they  are  all  contained 
in  the  Old.  Hence  Augustine  says  {Contra  Faust,  xix.)  that 
nearly  all  Our  Lord's  admonitions  or  precepts,  where  He 
expressed  Himself  by  saying :  *  But  I  say  unto  you,'  are  to 
be  found  also  in  those  ancient  books.     Yet,  since  they  thought 


301      NEW  LAW  COMPARED  WITH  OLD     Q.  107.  Art.  4 

that  murder  was  only  the  slaying  of  the  human  body,  Our  Lord 
declared  to  them  that  every  wicked  impulse  to  hurt  our  brother 
is  to  be  looked  on  as  a  kind  of  murder.  And  it  is  in  the  point 
of  declarations  of  this  kind  that  the  precepts  of  the  New 
Law  are  said  to  be  greater  than  those  of  the  Old.  Nothing, 
however,  prevents  the  greater  from  being  contained  in  the 
lesser  virtually;  just  as  a  tree  is  contained  in  the  seed. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  What  is  set  forth  implicitly  needs  to  be 
declared  explicitly.  Hence  after  the  publishing  of  the  Old 
Law,  a  New  Law  also  had  to  be  given. 


Fourth  Article, 
whether  the  new  law  is  more  burdensome  than 

THE    OLD  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  is  more  burden- 
some than  the  Old.  For  Chrysostom,  in  his  commentary 
on  Matth.  v.  19,  He  that  shall  break  one  of  these  least  com- 
mandments, says:  The  commandments  given  to  Moses  are 
easy  to  obey :  Thou  shall  not  kill ;  Thou  shall  not  commit 
adultery :  but  the  commandments  of  Christ  are  difficult  to 
accomplish,  for  instance  :  Thou  shall  not  give  way  to  anger, 
or  to  lust.  Therefore  the  New  Law  is  more  burdensome 
than  the  Old. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  it  is  easier  to  make  use  of  earthly  pros- 
perity than  to  suffer  tribulations.  But  in  the  Old  Testa- 
ment observance  of  the  Law  was  followed  by  temporal 
prosperity,  as  may  be  gathered  from  Deut.  xxviii.  1-14; 
whereas  many  kinds  of  trouble  ensue  to  those  who  observe 
the  New  Law,  as  stated  in  2  Cor.  vi.  4-10:  Let  us  exhibit 
ourselves  as  the  ministers  of  God,  in  much  patience,  in  tribula- 
tion, in  necessities,  in  distresses,  etc.  Therefore  the  New 
Law  is  more  burdensome  than  the  Old. 

Obj.  3.  The  more  one  has  to  do,  the  more  difficult  it  is. 
But  the  New  Law  is  something  added  to  the  Old.  For  the 
Old  Law  forbade  perjury,  while  the  New  Law  proscribed 
even  swearing:  the  Old  Law  forbade  a  man  to  cast  off  his 


Q.  107.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  302 

wife  without  a  bill  of  divorce,  while  the  New  Law  forbade 
divorce  altogether;  as  is  clearly  stated  in  Matth.  v.  31  seqq., 
according  to  Augustine's  expounding.  Therefore  the  New 
Law  is  more  burdensome  than  the  Old. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Matth.  xi.  28) :  Come  to  Me, 
all  you  that  labour  and  are  burdened  :  which  words  are  ex- 
pounded by  Hilary  thus:  He  calls  to  Himself  all  those  that 
labour  under  the  difficulty  of  observing  the  Law,  and  are  bur- 
dened with  the  sins  of  this  world.  And  further  on  He  says 
of  the  yoke  of  the  Gospel:  For  My  yoke  is  sweet  and  My 
burden  light.  Therefore  the  New  Law  is  a  lighter  burden 
than  the  Old. 

I  answer  that,  A  twofold  difficulty  may  attach  to  works 
of  virtue  with  which  the  precepts  of  the  Law  are  concerned. 
One  is  on  the  part  of  the  outward  works,  which  of  them- 
selves are,  in  a  way,  difficult  and  burdensome.  And  in  this 
respect  the  Old  Law  is  a  much  heavier  burden  than  the 
New:  since  the  Old  Law  by  its  numerous  ceremonies  pre- 
scribed many  more  outward  acts  than  the  New  Law,  which, 
in  the  teaching  of  Christ  and  the  apostles,  added  very  few 
precepts  to  those  of  the  natural  law;  although  afterwards 
some  were  added,  through  being  instituted  by  the  holy 
Fathers.  Even  in  these  Augustine  says  that  moderation 
should  be  observed,  lest  good  conduct  should  become  a 
burden  to  the  faithful.  For  he  says  in  reply  to  the  Queries 
of  Januarius  {Ep.  LV.)  that,  whereas  God  in  His  mercy 
wished  religion  to  be  a  free  service  rendered  by  the  public 
solemnization  of  a  small  number  of  most  manifest  sacraments, 
certain  persons  make  it  a  slave's  burden  ;  so  much  so  that  the 
state  of  the  Jews  who  were  subject  to  the  sacraments  of  the 
Law,  and  not  to  the  presumptuous  devices  of  man,  was  more 
tolerable. 

The  other  difficulty  attaches  to  works  of  virtue  as  to 
interior  acts:  for  instance,  that  a  virtuous  deed  be  done 
with  promptitude  and  pleasure.  It  is  this  difficulty  that 
virtue  solves:  because  to  act,  thus  is  difficult  for  a  man 
without  virtue:  but  through  virtue  it  becomes  easy  to  him. 
In  this  respect   the   precepts   of  the   New  Law  are  more 


303      NEW  LAW^  COMPARED  WITH  OLD    Q.  107.  Art.  4 

burdensome  than  those  of  the  Old;  because  the  New  Law 
prohibits  certain  interior  movements  of  the  soul,  which 
were  not  expressly  forbidden  in  the  Old  Law  in  all  cases, 
although  they  were  forbidden  in  some,  without,  however, 
any  punishment  being  attached  to  the  prohibition.  Now 
this  is  very  difficult  to  a  man  without  virtue:  thus  even  the 
Philosopher  states  {lithic.  v.)  that  it  is  easy  to  do  what  a 
righteous  man  does;  but  that  to  do  it  in  the  same  way, 
viz.,  with  pleasure  and  promptitude,  is  difficult  to  a  man 
who  is  not  righteous.  Accordingly  we  read  also  (i  John 
V.  3)  that  His  commandments  are  not  heavy  :  which  words 
Augustine  expounds  by  saying  that  they  are  not  heavy  to  the 
man  that  loveth  ;  whereas  they  are  a  burden  to  him  that  loveth 
not. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  passage  quoted  speaks  expressly  of  the 
difficulty  of  the  New  Law  as  to  the  deliberate  curbing  of 
interior  movements. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  tribulations  suffered  by  those  who 
observe  the  New  Law  are  not  imposed  by  the  Law  itself. 
Moreover  they  are  easily  borne,  on  account  of  the  love  in 
which  the  same  Law  consists:  since,  as  Augustine  says  in 
his  book  on  the  Lord's  words  (Serm.  Ixx.),  love  makes  light 
and  nothing  of  things  that  seem  arduous  and  beyond  our 
power. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  object  of  these  additions  to  the  precepts 
of  the  Old  Law  was  to  render  it  easier  to  do  what  it  pre- 
scribed, as  Augustine  states  (De  Serm.  Dom.  in  Monte  i.). 
Accordingly  this  does  not  prove  that  the  New  Law  is  more 
burdensome,  but  rather  that  it  is  a  lighter  burden. 


QUESTION  CVIII. 

OF  THOSE  THINGS  THAT  ARE  CONTAINED  IN  THE  NEW 

LAW. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  those  things  that  are  contained  in 
the  New  Law:  under  which  head  there  are  four  points  of 
inquiry:  (i)  Whether  the  New  Law  ought  to  prescribe  or 
to  forbid  any  outward  works  ?  (2)  Whether  the  New  Law 
makes  sufficient  provision  in  prescribing  and  forbidding 
external  acts  ?  (3)  Whether  in  the  matter  of  internal  acts 
it  directs  man  sufficiently  ?  (4)  Whether  it  fittingly  adds 
counsels  to  precepts  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  the  new  law  ought  to  prescribe  or  prohibit 

any  external  acts  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  should  not  pre- 
scribe or  prohibit  any  external  acts.  For  the  New  Law  is 
the  Gospel  of  the  kingdom,  according  to  Matth.  xxiv.  14: 
This  Gospel  of  the  kingdom  shall  he  preached  in  the  whole 
world.  But  the  kingdom  of  God  consists  not  in  exterior, 
but  only  in  interior  acts,  according  to  Luke  xvii.  21:  The 
kingdom  of  God  is  within  you  ;  and  Rom.  xiv.  17 :  The  kingdom 
of  God  is  not  meat  and  drink  ;  hut  justice  and  peace  and  joy 
in  the  Holy  Ghost.  Therefore  the  New  Law  should  not 
prescribe  or  forbid  any  external  acts. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  New  Law  is  the  law  of  the  Spirit 
(Rom.  viii.  2).     But  where  the  Spirit  of  the  Lord  is,  there  is 

304 


305  CONTENTS  OF  THE  NEW  LAW    Q.  io8.  Art.  i 

liberty  (2  Cor.  iii.  17).  Now  there  is  no  liberty  when  man  is 
bound  to  do  or  avoid  certain  external  acts.  Therefore  the 
New  Law  does  not  prescribe  or  forbid  any  external  acts. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  all  external  acts  are  understood  as  re- 
ferrible  to  the  hand,  just  as  interior  acts  belong  to  the 
mind.  But  this  is  assigned  as  the  difference  between  the 
New  and  Old  Laws  that  the  Old  Law  restrains  the  hand, 
whereas  the  New  Law  curbs  the  mind.  Therefore  the  New  Law 
should  not  contain  prohibitions  and  commands  about  ex- 
terior deeds,  but  only  about  interior  acts. 

On  the  contrary,  Through  the  New  Law,  men  are  made 
children  of  light :  wherefore  it  is  written  (John  xii.  36) : 
Believe  in  the  light  that  you  may  be  the  children  of  light.  Now 
it  is  becoming  that  children  of  the  light  should  do  deeds  of 
light  and  cast  aside  deeds  of  darkness,  according  to  Ephes. 
V.  8 :  You  were  heretofore  darkness,  but  now  light  in  the  Lord. 
Walk  .  .  .  as  children  of  the  light.  Therefore  the  New  Law 
had  to  forbid  certain  external  acts  and  prescribe  others. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (0.  CVL,  AA.  i,  2),  the  New 
Law  consists  chiefly  in  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  which 
is  shown  forth  by  faith  that  worketh  through  love.  Now 
men  become  receivers  of  this  grace  through  God's  Son 
made  man,  Whose  humanity  grace  filled  first,  and  thence 
flowed  forth  to  us.  Hence  it  is  written  (John  i.  14):  The 
Word  was  made  flesh,  and  afterwards : /w//  of  grace  and  truth  ; 
and  further  on :  Of  His  fulness  we  all  have  received,  and  grace 
for  grace.  Hence  it  is  added  that  grace  and  truth  came  by 
Jesus  Christ.  Consequently  it  was  becoming  that  the 
grace  which  flows  from  the  incarnate  Word  should  be  given 
to  us  by  means  of  certain  external  sensible  objects;  and  that 
from  this  inward  grace,  whereby  the  flesh  is  subjected  to 
the  Spirit,  certain  external  works  should  ensue. 

Accordingly  external  acts  may  have  a  twofold  connection 
with  grace.  In  the  first  place,  as  leading  in  some  way  to 
grace.  Such  are  the  sacramental  acts  which  are  instituted 
in  the  New  Law,  e.g..  Baptism,  the  Eucharist,  and  the 
like. 

In  the  second  place  there  are  those  external  acts  which 

II.  3  20 


Q.  io8.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  306 

ensue  from  the  promptings  of  grace:  and  herein  we  must 
observe  a  difference.     For  there  are  some  which  are  neces- 
sarily in  keeping  with,  or  in  opposition    to   inward  grace 
consisting  in  faith  that  worketh  through  love.     Such  ex- 
ternal works  are  prescribed  or  forbidden  in  the  New  Law; 
thus  confession  of  faith  is  prescribed,  and  denial  of  faith  is 
forbidden;  for  it  is  written  (Matth.  x.  32,  33):  [Every  one) 
that  shalt  confess  Me  before  men,  I  will  also  confess  him  before 
My  Father.  .  .  .     B^it  he  that  shall  deny  Me  before  men,  I  will 
also  deny  him  before  My  Father. — On  the  other  hand,  there 
are  works  which  are  not  necessarily  opposed  to,  or  in  keeping 
with  faith  that  worketh  through  love.     Such  works  are  not 
prescribed  or  forbidden  in  the  New  Law,  by  virtue  of  its 
primitive   institution;    but   have   been   left   by   the   Law- 
giver, i.e.,  Christ,  to  the  discretion  of  each  individual.     And 
so  to  each  one  it  is  free  to  decide  what  he  should  do  or 
avoid;  and  to  each  superior,  to  direct  his  subjects  in  such 
matters  as  regards  what  they  must  do  or  avoid.     Wherefore 
also  in  this  respect  the  Gospel  is  called  the  law  of  liberty 
(cf .  Reply  Obj.  2) :    since  the  Old  Law  decided  many  points 
and  left  few  to  man  to  decide  as  he  chose. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  kingdom  of  God  consists  chiefly  in  in- 
ternal acts :  but  as  a  consequence  all  things  that  are  essential 
to  internal  acts  belong  also  to  the  kingdom  of  God.  Thus 
if  the  kingdom  of  God  is  internal  righteousness,  peace,  and 
spiritual  joy,  all  external  acts  that  are  incompatible  with 
righteousness,  peace,  and  spiritual  joy,  are  in  opposition  to 
the  kingdom  of  God;  and  consequently  should  be  forbidden  in 
the  Gospel  of  the  kingdom.  On  the  other  hand,  those  things 
that  are  indifferent  as  regards  the  aforesaid,  for  instance, 
to  eat  of  this  or  that  food,  are  not  part  of  the  kingdom  of 
God;  wherefore  the  Apostle  says  before  the  words  quoted: 
21  le  kingdom  of  God  is  not  meat  and  drink. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  According  to  the  Philosopher  {Metaph.  i.) 
what  is  free  is  cause  of  itself.  Therefore  he  acts  freely,  who 
acts  of  his  own  accord.  Now  man  does  of  his  own  accord 
that  which  he  does  from  a  habit  that  is  suitable  to  his  nature: 
since  a  habit  inclines  one  as  a  second  nature.     If,  however,  a 


307  CONTENTS  OF  THE  NEW  LAW    Q.  io8.  Art.  2 

liabit  be  in  opposition  to  nature,  man  would  not  act  accord- 
ing to  his  nature,  but  according  to  some  corruption  affecting 
that  nature.  Since  then  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost  is 
like  an  interior  habit  bestowed  on  us  and  inclining  us  to 
act  aright,  it  makes  us  do  freely  those  things  that  are  be- 
coming to  grace,  and  shun  what  is  opposed  to  it. 

Accordingly  the  New  Law  is  called  the  law  of  liberty  in 
two  respects.  First,  because  it  does  not  bind  us  to  do  or 
avoid  certain  things,  except  such  as  are  of  themselves  neces- 
sary or  opposed  to  salvation,  and  come  under  the  pre- 
scription or  prohibition  of  the  law.  Secondly,  because  it 
also  makes  us  comply  freely  with  these  precepts  and  pro- 
hibitions, inasmuch  as  we  do  so  through  the  promptings 
of  grace.  It  is  for  these  two  reasons  that  the  New  Law  is 
called  the  law  of  perfect  liberty  (James  i.  25). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  New  Law,  by  restraining  the  mind  from 
inordinate  movements,  must  needs  also  restrain  the  hand 
from  inordinate  acts,  which  ensue  from  inward  movements. 


Second  Article. 

whether  the  new  law  made  sufficient  ordinations 
about  external  acts  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  made  insufhcient 
ordinations  about  external  acts.  Because  faith  that  worketh 
through  charity  seems  chiefly  to  belong  to  the  New  Law, 
according  to  Gal.  v.  6:  In  Christ  Jesus  neither  circumcision 
availeth  anything,  nor  uncircumcision  :  but  faith  that  worketh 
through  charity.  But  the  New  Law  declared  explicitly  cer- 
tain points  of  faith  which  were  not  set  forth  explicitly  in 
the  Old  Law;  for  instance,  belief  in  the  Trinity.  There- 
fore it  should  also  have  added  certain  outward  moral  deeds, 
which  were  not  fixed  in  the  Old  Law. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  in  the  Old  Law  not  only  were  sacraments 
instituted,  but  also  certain  sacred  things,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CL,  A.  4;  Q.  CIL,  A.  4).  But  in  the  New  Law,  although 
certain   sacraments   are   instituted,   yet   no   sacred   things 


Q.  io8.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  308 

seem  to  have  been  instituted  by  Our  Lord;  for  instance, 
pertaining  either  to  the  sanctification  of  a  temple  or  of  the 
vessels,  or  to  the  celebration  of  some  particular  feast. 
Therefore  the  New  Law  made  insufficient  ordinations  about 
external  matters. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  in  the  Old  Law,  just  as  there  were  certain 
observances  pertaining  to  God's  ministers,  so  also  were 
there  certain  observances  pertaining  to  the  people:  as  was 
stated  above  when  we  were  treating  of  the  ceremonial  of 
the  Old  Law  (Q.  CL,  A.  4;  Q.  GIL,  A.  6).  Now  in  the  New 
Law  certain  observances  seem  to  have  been  prescribed  to 
the  ministers  of  God;  as  may  be  gathered  from  Matth.  x.  9: 
Do  not  possess  gold,  nor  silver,  nor  money  in  your  purses,  nor 
other  things  which  are  mentioned  here  and  Luke  ix.,  x. 
Therefore  certain  observances  pertaining  to  the  faithful 
should  also  have  been  instituted  in  the  New  Law. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  in  the  Old  Law,  besides  moral  and  cere- 
monial precepts,  there  were  certain  judicial  precepts.  But 
in  the  New  Law  there  are  no  judicial  precepts.  Therefore 
the  New  Law  made  insufficient  ordinations  about  external 
works. 

On  the  contrary,  Our  Lord  said  (Matth.  vii.  24) :  Every  one 
.  .  .  that  heareth  these  My  words,  and  doth  them,  shall  he  likened 
to  a  wise  man  that  huilt  his  house  upon  a  rock.  But  a  wise 
builder  leaves  out  nothing  that  is  necessary  to  the  building. 
Therefore  Christ's  words  contain  all  things  necessary  for 
man's  salvation. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  the  New  Law  had 
to  make  such  prescriptions  or  prohibitions  alone  as  are 
essential  for  the  reception  or  right  use  of  grace.  And  since 
we  cannot  of  ourselves  obtain  grace,  but  through  Christ 
alone,  hence  Christ  of  Himself  instituted  the  sacraments 
whereby  we  obtain  grace:  viz.,  Baptism,  Eucharist,  Orders 
of  the  ministers  of  the  New  Law,  by  the  institution  of  the 
apostles  and  seventy-two  disciples,  Penance,  and  indis- 
soluble Matrimony.  He  promised  Confirmation  through 
the  sending  of  the  Holy  Ghost:  and  we  read  that  by  His 
institution  the  apostles  healed  the  sick  by  anointing  them 


309  CONTENTS  OF  THE  NEW  LAW     Q.  io8.  Art.  2 

with  oil  (Mark  v\.  13).  These  are  the  sacraments  of  the 
New  Law. 

The  right  use  of  grace  is  by  means  of  works  of  charity. 
These,  in  so  far  as  they  are  essential  to  virtue,  pertain  to 
the  moral  precepts,  which  also  formed  part  of  the  Old  Law. 
Hence,  in  this  respect,  the  New  Law  had  nothing  to  add  as 
regards  external  action. — The  determination  of  these  works 
in  their  relation  to  the  divine  worship,  belongs  to  the  cere- 
monial precepts  of  the  Law;  and,  in  relation  to  our  neigh- 
bour, to  the  judicial  precepts,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCIX., 
A.  4).  And  therefore,  since  these  determinations  are  not 
in  themselves  necessarily  connected  with  inward  grace 
wherein  the  Law  consists,  they  do  not  come  under  a 
precept  of  the  New  Law,  but  are  left  to  the  decision  of 
man;  some  relating  to  inferiors, — as  when  a  precept  is 
given  to  an  individual;  others,  relating  to  superiors, 
temporal  or  spiritual,  referring,  namely,  to  the  common 
good. 

Accordingly  the  New  Law  had  no  other  external  works 
to  determine,  by  prescribing  or  forbidding,  except  the  sacra- 
ments, and  those  moral  precepts  which  have  a  necessary 
connection  with  virtue,  for  instance,  that  one  must  not 
kill,  or  steal,  and  so  forth. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Matters  of  faith  are  above  human  reason, 
and  so  we  cannot  attain  to  them  except  through  grace. 
Consequently,  when  grace  came  to  be  bestowed  more  abun- 
dantly, the  result  was  an  increase  in  the  number  of  explicit 
points  of  faith.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is  through  human 
reason  that  we  are  directed  to  works  of  virtue,  for  it  is  the 
rule  of  human  action,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XIX.,  A.  3; 
Q.  LXHL,  A.  2).  Wherefore  in  such  matters  as  these  there 
was  no  need  for  any  precepts  to  be  given  besides  the  moral 
precepts  of  the  Law,  which  proceed  from  the  dictate  of 
reason. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  In  the  sacraments  of  the  New  Law  grace  is 
bestowed,  which  cannot  be  received  except  through  Christ: 
consequently  they  had  to  be  instituted  by  Him.  But  in 
the  sacred  things  no  grace  is  given:  for  instance,  in  the 


Q.  io8.  Art.  2      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  310 

consecration  of  a  temple,  an  altar  or  the  like,  or,  again,  in 
the  celebration  of  feasts.  Wherefore  Our  Lord  left  the 
institution  of  such  things  to  the  discretion  of  the  faithful, 
since  they  have  not  of  themselves  any  necessary  connection 
with  inward  grace. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Our  Lord  gave  the  apostles  those  precepts 
not  as  ceremonial  observances,  but  as  moral  statutes:  and 
they  can  be  understood  in  two  ways.  First,  following 
Augustine  [De  Consensu  Evang.  xxx.),  as  being  not  com- 
mands, but  permissions.  For  He  permitted  them  to  set 
forth  to  preach  without  scrip  or  stick,  and  so  on,  since 
they  were  empowered  to  accept  their  livelihood  from  those 
to  whom  they  preached:  wherefore  He  goes  on  to  say: 
For  the  labourer  is  worthy  of  his  hire.  Nor  is  it  a  sin,  but  a 
work  of  supererogation  for  a  preacher  to  take  means  of 
livelihood  with  him,  without  accepting  supplies  from  those 
to  whom  he  preaches;  as  Paul  did  (i  Cor.  ix.  4,  seqq.). 

Secondly,  according  to  the  explanation  of  other  holy 
men,  they  may  be  considered  as  temporal  commands  laid 
upon  the  apostles  for  the  time  during  which  they  were 
sent  to  preach  in  Judea  before  Christ's  Passion.  For  the 
disciples,  being  yet  as  little  children  under  Christ's  care, 
needed  to  receive  some  special  commands  from  Christ,  such 
as  all  subjects  receive  from  their  superiors:  and  especially 
so,  since  they  were  to  be  accustomed  little  by  little  to  re- 
nounce the  care  of  temporalities,  so  as  to  become  fitted  for  the 
preaching  of  the  Gospel  throughout  the  whole  world.  Nor 
must  we  wonder  if  He  established  certain  fixed  modes  of 
life,  as  long  as  the  state  of  the  Old  Law  endured  and  the 
people  had  not  as  yet  achieved  the  perfect  liberty  of  the 
Spirit.  These  statutes  He  abolished  shortly  before  His 
Passion,  as  though  the  disciples  had  by  their  means  become 
sufficiently  practised.  Hence  He  said  (Luke  xxii.  35,  26) : 
When  I  sent  you  without  purse  and  scrip  and  shoes,  did  you 
want  anything  ?  But  they  said  :  Nothing.  Then  said  He 
unto  them  :  But  now,  he  that  hath  a  purse,  let  him  take  it,  and 
likewise  a  scrip.  Because  the  time  of  perfect  liberty  was 
already  at  hand,  when  they  would  be  left  entirely  to  their 


311  CONTENTS  OF  THE  NEW  LAW    Q.  io8.  Art.  3 

own  judgment  in  matters  not  necessarily  connected  with 
virtue. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  Judicial  precepts  also,  are  not  essential  to 
virtue  in  respect  of  any  particular  determination,  but  only 
in  regard  to  the  common  notion  of  justice.  Consequently 
Our  Lord  left  the  judicial  precepts  to  the  discretion  of 
those  who  were  to  have  spiritual  or  temporal  charge  of 
others.  But  as  regards  the  judicial  precepts  of  the  Old 
Law,  some  of  them  He  explained,  because  they  were  mis- 
understood by  the  Pharisees,  as  we  shall  state  later  on 
(A.  3,  ad  2). 

Third  Article. 

whether  the  new  law  directed  man  sufficiently  as 
regards  interior  actions  ? 

Wc  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  New  Law  directed  man  in- 
sufficiently as  regards  interior  actions.  For  there  are  ten 
commandments  of  the  decalogue  directing  man  to  God  and 
his  neighbour.  But  Our  Lord  partly  fulfilled  only  three  of 
them:  as  regards,  namely,  the  prohibition  of  murder,  of 
adultery,  and  of  perjury.  Therefore  it  seems  that,  by 
omitting  to  fulfil  the  other  precepts,  He  directed  man 
insufficiently. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  as  regards  the  judicial  precepts,  Our 
Lord  ordained  nothing  in  the  Gospel,  except  in  the  matter 
of  divorcing  a  wife,  of  punishment  by  retaliation,  and 
of  persecuting  one's  enemies.  But  there  are  many  other 
judicial  precepts  of  the  Old  Law,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CIV., 
A.  4;  Q.  CV.).  Therefore,  in  this  respect,  He  directed 
human  life  insufficiently. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  in  the  Old  Law,  besides  moral  and 
judicial,  there  were  ceremonial  precepts  about  which  Our 
Lord  made  no  ordination.  Therefore  it  seems  that  He 
ordained  insufficiently. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  in  order  that  the  mind  be  inwardly  well 
disposed,  man  should  do  no  good  deed  for  any  temporal 
end  whatever.     But  there  are  many  other  temporal  goods 


Q.  io8.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGTCA  "  312 

besides  the  favour  of  man:  and  there  are  many  other  good 
works  besides  fasting,  alms-deeds,  and  prayer.  Therefore 
Our  Lord  unbecomingly  taught  that  only  in  respect  of 
these  three  works,  and  of  no  other  earthly  goods  ought  we 
to  shun  the  glory  of  human  favour. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  solicitude  for  the  necessary  means  of 
livelihood  is  by  nature  instilled  into  man,  and  this  solicitude 
even  other  animals  share  with  man:  wherefore  it  is  written 
(Prov.  vi.  6,  S):  Go  to  the  ant,  0  sluggard,  and  consider  her 
ways  .  .  .  she  provideth  her  meat  for  herself  in  the  summer,  and 
gather eth  her  food  in  the  harvest.  But  every  command  issued 
against  the  inclination  of  nature  is  an  unjust  command, 
forasmuch  as  it  is  contrary  to  the  law  of  nature.  Therefore 
it  seems  that  Our  Lord  unbecomingly  forbade  solicitude 
about  food  and  raiment. 

Obj.  6.  Further,  no  act  of  virtue  should  be  the  subject 
of  a  prohibition.  Now  judgment  is  an  act  of  justice,  ac- 
cording to  Ps.  xciii.  15 :  Until  justice  be  turned  into  judgment. 
Therefore  it  seems  that  Our  Lord  unbecomingly  forbade 
judgment:  and  consequently  that  the  New  Law  directed 
man  insufficiently  in  the  matter  of  interior  acts. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [De  Serm.  Dom.  in 
Monte,  i.):  We  should  take  note  that,  when  He  said:  *  He 
that  hear  eth  these  My  words,'  He  indicates  clearly  that  this 
sermon  of  the  Lord  is  replete  with  all  the  precepts  whereby  a 
Christian's  life  is  formed. 

I  answer  that.  As  is  evident  from  Augustine's  words  just 
quoted,  the  sermon,  which  Our  Lord  delivered  on  the  moun- 
tain, contains  the  whole  process  of  forming  the  life  of  a 
Christian.  Therein  man's  interior  movements  are  ordered. 
Because  after  declaring  that  his  end  is  Beatitude ;  and  after 
commending  the  authority  of  the  apostles,  through  whom 
the  teaching  of  the  Gospel  was  to  be  promulgated.  He 
orders  man's  interior  movements,  first  in  regard  to  man 
himself,  secondly  in  regard  to  his  neighbour. 

This  he  does  in  regard  to  man  himself,  in  two  ways,  cor- 
responding to  man's  two  interior  movements  in  respect  of 
any  prospective  action,  viz.,  volition  of  what  has  to  be 


313  CONTENTS  OF  THK  NEW  LAW    Q.  to8.  Art.  3 

done,  and  intention  of  the  end.  Wherefore,  in  the  first 
place.  He  directs  man's  will  in  respect  of  the  various  pre- 
cepts of  the  Law:  by  prescribing  that  man  should  refrain 
not  merely  from  those  external  works  that  are  evil  in  them- 
selves, but  also  from  (the  corresponding)  internal  acts,  and 
from  the  occasions  of  evil  deeds.  In  the  second  place  He 
directs  man's  intention,  by  teaching  that  in  our  good  works, 
we  should  seek  neither  human  praise,  nor  worldly  riches, 
which  is  to  lay  up  treasures  on  earth. 

Afterwards  He  directs  man's  interior  movement  in  re- 
spect of  his  neighbour,  by  forbidding  us,  on  the  one  hand, 
to  judge  him  rashly,  unjustly,  or  presumptuously;  and, 
on  the  other,  to  entrust  him  too  readily  with  sacred  things 
if  he  be  unworthy. 

Lastly,  He  teaches  us  how  to  fulfil  the  teaching  of  the 
Gospel;  viz.,  by  imploring  the  help  of  God;  by  striving  to 
enter  by  the  narrow  door  of  perfect  virtue;  and  by  being 
wary  lest  we  be  led  astray  by  evil  influences.  Moreover,  He 
declares  that  we  must  observe  His  commandments,  and  that 
it  is  not  enough  to  make  profession  of  faith,  or  to  work 
miracles,  or  merely  to  hear  His  words. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Our  Lord  explained  the  manner  of  fulfilling 
those  precepts  which  the  Scribes  and  Pharisees  did  not 
rightly  understand:  and  this  affected  chiefly  those  precepts 
of  the  decalogue.  For  they  thought  that  the  prohibition 
of  adultery  and  murder  covered  the  external  act  only,  and 
not  the  internal  desire.  And  they  held  this  opinion  about 
murder  and  adultery  rather  than  about  theft  and  false 
witness,  because  the  movement  of  anger  tending  to  murder, 
and  the  movement  of  desire  tending  to  adultery,  seem  to 
be  in  us  from  nature  somewhat,  but  not  the  desire  of  stealing 
or  of  bearing  false  witness. — They  held  a  false  opinion  about 
perjury,  for  they  thought  that  perjury  indeed  was  a  sin; 
but  that  oaths  were  of  themselves  to  be  desired  and  to  be 
taken  frequently,  since  they  seem  to  proceed  from  reverence 
to  God.  Hence  Our  Lord  shows  that  an  oath  is  not  desirable 
as  a  good  thing ;  and  that  it  is  better  to  speak  without  oaths, 
unless  necessity  forces  us  to  have  recourse  to  them. 


Q.  io8.  Art.  3      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  314 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  Scribes  and  Pharisees  erred  about  the 
judicial  precepts  in  two  ways.  First,  because  they  con- 
sidered certain  matters  contained  in  the  Law  of  Moses  by 
way  of  permission,  to  be  right  in  themselves:  namely, 
divorce  of  a  wife,  and  the  taking  of  usury  from  strangers. 
Wherefore  Our  Lord  forbade  a  man  to  divorce  his  wife 
(Matth.  V.  32) ;  and  to  receive  usury  (Luke  vi.  35),  when  He 
said:  Lend,  hoping  for  nothing  thereby. 

In  another  way  they  erred  by  thinking  that  certain  things 
which  the  Old  Law  commanded  to  be  done  for  justice'  sake, 
should  be  done  out  of  desire  for  revenge,  or  out  of  lust  for 
temporal  goods,  or  out  of  hatred  of  one's  enemies ;  and  this 
in  respect  of  three  precepts.  For  they  thought  that  desire 
for  revenge  was  lawful,  on  account  of  the  precept  concern- 
ing punishment  by  retaliation:  whereas  this  precept  was 
given  that  justice  might  be  safeguarded,  not  that  man  might 
seek  revenge.  Wherefore,  in  order  to  do  away  with  this, 
Our  Lord  teaches  that  man  should  be  prepared  in  his 
mind  to  suffer  yet  more  if  necessary. — They  thought  that 
movements  of  covetousness  were  lawful,  on  account  of  those 
judicial  precepts  which  prescribed  restitution  of  what  had 
been  purloined,  together  with  something  added  thereto, 
as  stated  above  (0.  CV.,  A.  2,  ad  9);  whereas  the  Law  com- 
manded this  to  be  done  in  order  to  safeguard  justice,  not 
to  encourage  covetousness.  Wherefore  Our  Lord  teaches 
that  we  should  not  demand  our  goods  from  motives  ol 
cupidity,  and  that  we  should  be  ready  to  give  yet  more  if 
necessary. — ^They  thought  that  the  movement  of  hatred  was 
lawful,  on  account  of  the  commandments  of  the  Law  about 
the  slaying  of  one's  enemies:  whereas  the  Law  ordered 
this  for  the  fulfilment  of  justice,  as  stated  above  (0.  CV., 
A.  3,  ad  4),  not  to  satisfy  hatred.  Wherefore  Our  Lord 
teaches  us  that  we  ought  to  love  our  enemies,  and  to  be 
ready  to  do  good  to  them  if  necessary.  For  these  precepts 
are  to  be  taken  as  binding  the  mind  to  he  prepared  to  fulfil 
them,  as  Augustine  says  {ibid.). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  moral  precepts  necessarily  retained  their 
force  under  the  New  Law,  because  they  are  of  themselves 


315  CONTENTS  OF  THE  NEW  LAW     Q.  io8.  Art.  3 

essential  to  virtue:  whereas  the  judicial  precepts  did  not 
necessarily  continue  to  bind  in  exactly  the  same  way  as  had 
been  fixed  by  the  Law :  this  was  left  to  man  to  decide  in 
one  way  or  another.  Hence  Our  Lord  directed  us  be- 
comingly with  regard  to  these  two  kinds  of  precepts.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  observance  of  the  ceremonial  precepts 
was  totally  abolished  by  the  advent  of  the  reality;  where- 
fore in  regard  to  these  precepts  He  commanded  nothing 
on  this  occasion  when  He  was  giving  the  general  points  of 
His  doctrine.  Elsewhere,  however,  He  makes  it  clear  that 
the  entire  bodily  worship  which  was  fixed  by  the  Law,  was 
to  be  changed  into  a  spiritual  worship:  as  is  evident  from 
John  iv.  21,  23,  where  He  says  ;  The  hour  cometh  when  you 
shall  neither  on  this  mountain,  nor  in  Jerusalem  adore  the 
Father  .  .  .  hut  .  .  .  the  true  adorers  shall  adore  the  Father  in 
spirit  and  in  truth. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  All  worldly  goods  may  be  reduced  to  three, — 
honours,  riches,  and  pleasures;  according  to  i  John  ii.  16: 
All  that  is  in  the  world  is  the  concupiscence  of  the  flesh,  which 
refers  to  pleasures  of  the  flesh,  and  the  concupiscence  of  the 
eyes,  which  refers  to  riches,  and  the  pride  of  life,  which  refers 
to  ambition  for  renown  and  honour.  Now  the  Law  did  not 
promise  an  abundance  of  carnal  pleasures;  on  the  contrary, 
it  forbade  them.  But  it  did  promise  exalted  honours  and 
abundant  riches ;  for  it  is  written  in  reference  to  the  former 
(Deut.  xxviii.  i) :  //  thou  wilt  hear  the  voice  of  the  Lord  thy 
God,  .  .  .  He  will  make  thee  higher  than  all  the  nations  ;  and 
in  reference  to  the  latter,  we  read  a  little  further  on  [verse  11)  : 
He  will  make  thee  abound  with  all  goods.  But  the  Jews 
so  distorted  the  true  meaning  of  these  promises,  as  to 
think  that  we  ought  to  serve  God,  with  these  things  as  the 
end  in  view.  Wherefore  Our  Lord  set  this  aside  by  teach- 
ing, first  of  all,  that  works  of  virtue  should  not  be  done  for 
human  glory.  And  He  mentions  three  works,  to  which  all 
others  may  be  reduced :  since  whatever  a  man  does  in  order 
to  curb  his  desires,  comes  under  the  head  of  fasting;  and 
whatever  a  man  does  for  the  love  of  his  neighbour,  comes 
under  the  head  of  alms-deeds;  and  whatever  a  man  does  for 


Q.  io8.  Art.  3       THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGTCA  "  316 

the  worship  of  God,  comes  under  the  head  of  prayer.  And 
He  mentions  these  three  specially,  as  they  hold  the  princi- 
pal place,  and  are  most  often  used  by  men  in  order  to 
gain  glory. — In  the  second  place  He  taught  us  that  we  must 
not  place  our  end  in  riches,  when  He  said:  Lay  not  up  to 
yourselves  treasures  on  earth  (Matth.  vi.  19). 

Reply  Ohj .  5.  Our  Lord  forbade,  not  necessary  but  in- 
ordinate solicitude.  Now  there  is  a  fourfold  solicitude  to 
be  avoided  in  temporal  matters.  First,  we  must  not  place 
our  end  in  them,  nor  serve  God  for  the  sake  of  the  neces- 
sities of  food  and  raiment.  Wherefore  He  says:  Lay  not 
up  for  yourselves,  etc. — Secondly,  we  must  not  be  so  anxious 
about  temporal  things,  as  to  despair  of  God's  help:  wherefore 
Our  Lord  says  [ibid.  32) :  Your  Father  knoweth  that  you  have 
need  of  all  these  things. — Thirdly,  we  must  not  add  pre- 
sumption to  our  solicitude;  in  other  words,  we  must  not 
be  confident  of  getting  the  necessaries  of  life  by  our  own 
efforts  without  God's  help:  such  solicitude  Our  Lord  sets 
aside  by  saying  that  a  man  cannot  add  anything  to  his 
stature  [ihid.  27). — We  must  not  anticipate  the  time  of 
anxiety ;  namely,  by  being  solicitous  now,  for  the  needs,  not 
of  the  present,  but  of  a  future  time:  wherefore  He  says 
[ihid.  34):  Be  not  .  .  .  solicitous  for  to-morrow. 

Reply  Ohj.  6.  Our  Lord  did  not  forbid  the  judgment  of 
justice,  without  which  holy  things  could  not  be  withdrawn 
from  the  unworthy.  But  he  forbade  inordinate  judgment, 
as  stated  above. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  certain  definite  counsels  are  fittingly 
proposed  in  the  new  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  certain  definite  counsels  are 
not  fittingly  proposed  in  the  New  Law.  For  counsels  are 
given  about  that  which  is  expedient  for  an  end,  as  we  stated 
above,  when  treating  of  coimsel  (Q.  XIV.,  A.  2).  But  the 
same  things  are  not  expedient  for  all.  Therefore  certain 
definite  counsels  should  not  be  proposed  to  all. 


317  CONTENTS  OF  THE  NEW  LAW    u.  io8.  Art.  4 

Ubj.  2.  Further,  counsels  regard  a  greater  good.  But 
there  are  no  delhiite  degrees  oi  the  greater  good.  There- 
fore dehnite  counsels  should  not  be  given. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  counsels  pertain  to  the  life  of  perfection. 
But  obedience  pertains  to  the  life  of  perfection.  Therefore 
it  was  unfitting  that  no  counsel  of  obedience  should  be 
contained  in  the  Gospel. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  many  matters  pertaining  to  the  life  of 
perfection  are  found  among  the  commandments,  as,  for 
instance.  Love  your  enonics  (Matth.  v.  44),  and  those  pre- 
cepts NNliich  Our  Lord  gave  His  apostles  (ibid.  x.).  There- 
fore the  counsels  are  unfittingly  given  in  the  New  Law: 
both  because  they  are  not  all  mentioned;  and  because  they 
are  not  distinguished  from  the  commandments. 

On  the  contrary,  The  counsels  of  a  wise  friend  are  of  great 
use,  according  to  Prov.  xxvii.  9:  Ointment  and  perfumes 
rejoice  the  heart  :  and  the  good  counsels  of  a  friend  rejoice  the 
soul.  But  Christ  is  our  wisest  and  greatest  friend.  There- 
fore His  counsels  are  supremely  useful  and  becoming. 

/  answer  that,  The  difference  between  a  counsel  and  a  com- 
mandment is  that  a  commandment  implies  obligation, 
whereas  a  counsel  is  left  to  the  option  of  the  one  to  whom 
it  is  given.  Consequently  in  the  New  Law,  which  is  the  law 
of  liberty,  counsels  are  added  to  the  commandments,  and 
not  in  the  Old  Law,  which  is  the  law  of  bondage.  We  must 
therefore  understand  the  commandments  of  the  New  Law 
to  have  been  given  about  matters  that  are  necessary  to  gain 
the  end  of  eternal  bliss,  to  which  end  the  New  Law  brings 
us  forthwith:  but  that  the  counsels  are  about  matters  that 
render  the  gaining  of  this  end  more  assured  and  expeditious. 

Now  man  is  placed  between  the  things  of  this  world,  and 
spiritual  goods  wherein  eternal  happiness  consists:  so  that 
the  more  he  cleaves  to  the  one,  the  more  he  withdraws 
from  the  other,  and  conversely.  Wherefore  he  that  cleaves 
wholly  to  the  things  of  this  world,  so  as  to  make  them  his 
end,  and  to  look  upon  them  as  the  reason  and  rule  of  all  he 
does,  falls  away  altogether  from  spiritual  goods.  Hence 
this  disorder  is  removed  by  the  commandments.     Never- 


Q.  io8.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  318 

theless,  for  man  to  gain  the  end  aforesaid,  he  does  not 
need  to  renounce  the  things  of  the  world  altogether:  since 
he  can,  while  using  the  things  of  this  world,  attain  to 
eternal  happiness,  provided  he  does  not  place  his  end  in 
them:  but  he  will  attain  more  speedily  thereto  by  giving 
up  the  goods  of  this  world  entirely:  wherefore  the  evan- 
gelical counsels  are  given  for  this  purpose. 

Now  the  goods  of  this  world  which  come  into  use  in  human 
life,  consist  in  three  things:  viz.,  in  external  wealth  per- 
taining to  the  concupiscence  of  the  eyes  ;  carnal  pleasures 
pertaining  to  the  concupiscence  of  the  flesh  ;  and  honours, 
which  pertain  to  the  pride  of  life,  according  to  i  John 
ii.  16:  and  it  is  in  renouncing  these  altogether,  as  far  as 
possible,  that  the  evangelical  counsels  consist.  Moreover, 
every  form  of  the  religious  life  that  professes  the  state  of 
perfection  is  based  on  these  three :  since  riches  are  renounced 
by  poverty;  carnal  pleasures  by  perpetual  chastity;  and  the 
pride  of  life  by  the  bondage  of  obedience. 

Now  if  a  man  observe  these  absolutely,  this  is  in  accord- 
ance with  the  counsels  as  they  stand.  But  if  a  man  observe 
any  one  of  them  in  a  particular  case,  this  is  taking  that 
counsel  in  a  restricted  sense,  namely,  as  applying  to  that 
particular  case.  For  instance,  when  anyone  gives  an  alms 
to  a  poor  man,  not  being  bound  so  to  do,  he  follows  the 
counsels  in  that  particular  case.  In  like  manner,  when 
a  man  for  some  fixed  time  refrains  from  carnal  pleasures 
that  he  may  give  himself  to  prayer,  he  follows  the  counsel 
for  that  particular  time.  And  again,  when  a  man  follows 
not  his  will  as  to  some  deed  which  he  might  do  lawfully, 
he  follows  the  counsel  in  that  particular  case :  for  instance, 
if  he  do  good  to  his  enemies  when  he  is  not  bound  to,  or  if 
he  forgive  an  injury  of  which  he  might  justly  seek  to  be 
avenged.  In  this  way,  too,  all  particular  counsels  may  be 
reduced  to  these  three  general  and  perfect  counsels. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  aforesaid  counsels,  considered  in  them- 
selves, are  expedient  to  all;  but  owing  to  some  people  being 
ill-disposed,  it  happens  that  some  of  them  are  inexpedient, 
because  their  disposition  is  not  inclined  to  such  things. 


319  CONTENTS  OF  THE  NEW  LAW    Q.  io8.  Akt.  4 

Hence  Our  Lord,  in  proposing  the  evangelical  counsels, 
always  makes  mention  of  man's  fitness  for  observing  the 
counsels.  For  in  giving  the  counsel  of  perpetual  poverty 
(Matth.  xix.  21),  He  begins  with  the  words:  If  thou  wilt  be 
perfect,  and  then  He  adds:  Go  sell  all  thou  hast.  In  like 
manner  when  He  gave  the  coimsel  of  perpetual  chastity, 
saying  {ibid.,  12):  There  are  eunuchs  who  have  made  them- 
selves eunuchs  for  the  kingdom  of  heaven,  He  adds  straight- 
way: He  that  can  take,  let  him  take  it.  And,  again,  the 
Apostle  (i  Cor.  vii.  35),  after  giving  the  counsel  of  virginity, 
says:  And  this  I  speak  for  your  profit ;  not  to  cast  a  snare 
upon  you. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  greater  goods  are  not  definitely  fixed 
in  the  individual ;  but  those  which  are  simply  and  absolutely 
the  greater  good  in  general  are  fixed:  and  to  these  all  the 
above  particular  goods  may  be  reduced,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Even  the  counsel  of  obedience  is  understood 
to  have  been  given  by  Our  Lord  in  the  words:  And  (let  him) 
follow  Me.  For  we  follow  Him  not  only  by  imitating  His 
works,  but  also  by  obeying  His  commandments,  according 
to  John  x.  27:  My  sheep  hear  My  voice  .  .  .  and  they  follow 
Me. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Those  things  which  Our  Lord  prescribed 
about  the  true  love  of  our  enemies,  and  other  similar  sayings 
(Matth.  v.,  Luke  vi.),  may  be  referred  to  the  preparation 
of  the  mind,  and  then  they  are  necessary  for  salvation ;  for 
instance,  that  man  be  prepared  to  do  good  to  his  enemies, 
and  other  similar  actions,  when  there  is  need.  Hence 
these  things  are  placed  among  the  precepts.  But  that  any- 
one should  actually  and  promptly  behave  thus  towards  an 
enemy  when  there  is  no  special  need,  is  to  be  referred  to  the 
particular  counsels,  as  stated  above. — As  to  those  matters 
which  are  set  down  in  Matth.  x.  and  Luke  ix.  andx.,  they 
were  either  disciplinary  commands  for  that  particular  time, 
or  concessions,  as  stated  above  (A.  2  ad  ^).  Hence  they  are 
not  set  down  among  the  counsels. 


TREATISE  ON  GRACE 


II.  3  21 


QUESTION  CIX. 

OF  THE  NECESSITY  OF  GRACE. 

{In  Ten  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  exterior  principle  of  human 
acts,  i.e.,  God,  in  so  far  as,  through  grace,  we  are  helped  by 
Him  to  do  right:  and,  first,  we  must  consider  the  grace  of 
God;  secondly,  its  cause;  thirdly,  its  effects. 

The  first  point  of  consideration  will  be  threefold;  for  we 
shall  consider  (i)  The  necessity  of  grace;  (2)  grace  itself, 
as  to  its  essence;  (3)  its  division. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  ten  points  of  inquiry — 
(i)  Whether  without  grace  man  can  know  anything  ? 
(2)  Whether  without  God's  grace  man  can  do  or  wish  any 
good  ?  (3)  Whether  without  grace  man  can  love  God  above 
all  things  ?  (4)  Whether  without  grace  man  can  keep  the 
commandments  of  the  Law  ?  (5)  Whether  without  grace 
he  can  merit  eternal  life  ?  (6)  Whether  without  grace  man 
can  prepare  himself  for  grace  ?  (7)  Whether  without  grace 
he  can  rise  from  sin  ?  (8)  Whether  without  grace  man  can 
avoid  sin  ?  (9)  Whether  man  having  received  grace  can  do 
good  and  avoid  sin  without  any  further  Divine  help  ? 
(10)  Whether  he  can  of  himself  persevere  in  good  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  without  grace  man  can  know  any  truth  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  without  grace  man  can  know 
no  truth.  For,  on  i  Cor.  xii.  3:  No  man  can  say,  the  Lord 
Jesus,  but  by  the  Holy  Ghost,  the  gloss  says:  Every  truth,  by 

323 


Q.  log.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  324 

whomsoever  spoken  is  from  the  Holy  Ghost.  Now  the  Holy 
Ghost  dwells  in  us  by  grace.  Therefore  we  cannot  know 
truth  without  grace. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Augustine  says  [SoUl.  i.)  that  the  most 
certain  sciences  are  like  things  lit  up  by  the  sun  so  as  to  he 
seen.  Now  God  Himself  is  He  Who  sheds  the  light.  And 
reason  is  in  the  mind  as  sight  is  in  the  eye.  And  the  eyes  of  the 
mind  are  the  senses  of  the  soul.  Now  the  bodily  senses,  how- 
ever pure,  cannot  see  any  visible  object,  without  the  sun's 
light.  Therefore  the  human  mind,  however  perfect,  cannot, 
by  reasoning,  know  any  truth  without  Divine  light :  and  this 
pertains  to  the  aid  of  grace. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  human  mind  can  only  understand 
truth  by  thinking,  as  is  clear  from  Augustine  [De  Trin.  xiv.). 
But  the  Apostle  says  (2  Cor.  iii.  5) :  Not  that  we  are  sufficient  to 
think  anything  of  ourselves,  as  of  ourselves  ;  hut  our  sufficiency 
is  from  God.  Therefore  man  cannot,  of  himself,  know  truth 
without  the  help  of  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [Retract,  i.) :  /  do  not 
approve  having  said  in  the  prayer,  0  God,  Who  dost  wish  the 
sinless  alone  to  know  the  truth  ;  for  it  may  he  answered  that 
many  who  are  not  sinless  know  many  truths.  Now  man  is 
cleansed  from  sin  by  grace,  according  to  Ps.  1.  12 :  Create  a 
clean  heart  in  me,  0  God,  and  renew  a  right  spirit  within  my 
bowels.  Therefore  without  grace  man  of  himself  can  know 
truth. 

/  answer  that.  To  know  truth  is  a  use  or  act  of  intellectual 
light,  since,  according  to  the  Apostle  (Eph.  v.  13) :  All  that 
is  made  manifest  is  light.  Now  every  use  implies  movement, 
taking  movement  broadly,  so  as  to  call  thinking  and  willing 
movements,  as  is  clear  from  the  Philosopher  [De  Anima,  iii.). 
Now  in  corporeal  things  we  see  that  for  movement  there  is 
required  not  merely  the  form  which  is  the  principle  of  the 
movement  or  action,  but  there  is  also  required  the  motion 
of  the  first  mover.  Now  the  first  mover  in  the  order  of 
corporeal  things  is  the  heavenly  body.  Hence  no  matter 
how  perfectly  fire  has  heat,  it  would  not  bring  about  altera- 
tion, except  by  the  motion  of  the  heavenly  body.     But  it 


325  THE  NECESSITY  OF  GRACE    Q.  109.  Art.  i 

is  clear  that  as  all  corporeal  movements  are  reduced  to  the 
motion  of  the  heavenly  body  as  to  the  first  corporeal  mover, 
so  all  movements,  both  corporeal  and  spiritual,  are  re- 
duced to  the  simple  First  Mover,  Who  is  God.  And  hence 
no  matter  how  perfect  a  corporeal  or  spiritual  nature  is  sup- 
posed to  be,  it  cannot  proceed  to  its  act  unless  it  be  moved 
by  God;  but  this  motion  is  according  to  the  plan  of  His 
providence,  and  not  by  a  necessity  of  nature,  as  the  motion 
of  the  heavenly  body.  Now  not  only  is. every  motion  from 
God  as  from  the  First  Mover,  but  all  formal  perfection  is 
from  Him  as  from  the  First  Act.  And  thus  the  act  of  the 
intellect  or  of  any  created  being  whatsoever  depends  upon 
God  in  two  ways :  first,  inasmuch  as  it  is  from  Him  that  it 
has  the  form  whereby  it  acts  ;  secondly,  inasmuch  as  it  is 
moved  by  Him  to  act. 

Now  every  form  bestowed  on  created  things  by  God  has 
power  for  a  determined  act,  which  it  can  bring  about  in  pro- 
portion to  its  own  proper  endowment;  and  beyond  which 
it  is  powerless,  except  by  a  superadded  form,  as  water  can 
only  heat  when  heated  by  the  fire.  And  thus  the  human  / 
understanding  has  a  form,  viz.,  intelligible  light,  which  of 
itself  is  sufficient  for  knowing  certain  intelligible  things, 
viz.,  those  we  can  come  to  know  through  the  senses.  Higher 
intelligible  things  the  human  intellect  cannot  know,  unless 
it  be  perfected  by  a  stronger  light,  viz.,  the  light  of  faith 
or  prophecy  which  is  called  the  light  of  grace,  inasmuch  as  ^ 
it  is  added  to  nature. 

Hence  we  must  say  that  for  the  knowledge  of  any  truth 
whatsoever  man  needs  Divine  help,  that  the  intellect  may 
be  moved  by  God  to  its  act.  But  he  does  not  need  a  new 
light  added  to  his  natural  light,  in  order  to  know  the  truth 
in  all  things,  but  only  in  some  that  surpass  his  natural  know- 
ledge. And  yet  at  times  God  miraculously  instructs  some 
by  His  grace  in  things  that  can  be  known  by  natural  reason, 
even  as  He  sometimes  brings  about  miraculously  what 
nature  can  do. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Every  truth  by  whomsoever  spoken  is  from 
the  Holy  Ghost  as  bestowing  the  natural  light,  and  moving 


Q.  109  Art.  2     THi:  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  326 

us  to  understand  and  speak  the  truth,  but  not  as  dwelHng 
in  us  by  sanctifying  grace,  or  as  bestowing  any  habitual 
gift  superadded  to  nature.  For  this  only  takes  place  with 
regard  to  certain  truths  that  are  known  and  spoken,  and 
especially  in  regard  to  such  as  pertain  to  faith,  of  which  the 
Apostle  speaks. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  material  sun  sheds  its  light  outside  us; 
but  the  intelligible  Sun,  Who  is  God,  shines  within  us. 
Hence  the  natural  light  bestowed  upon  the  soul  is  God's 
enlightenment,  whereby  we  are  enlightened  to  see  what 
pertains  to  natural  knowledge;  and  for  this  there  is  re- 
quired no  further  knowledge,  but  only  for  such  things  as 
surpass  natural  knowledge. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  We  always  need  God's  help  for  every 
thought,  inasmuch  as  He  moves  the  understanding  to  act ; 
for  actually  to  understand  anything  is  to  think,  as  is  clear 
from  Augustine  [De  Trin.  xiv.). 

Second  Article, 
whether  man  can  wish  or  do  any  good  without  grace  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article: — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man  can  wish  and  do  good 
without  grace.  For  that  is  in  man's  power,  whereof  he  is 
master.  Now  man  is  master  of  his  acts,  and  especially  of 
his  willing,  as  stated  above  (Q.  L,  A.  i;  Q.  XHL,  A.  6). 
Hence  man,  of  himself,  can  wish  and  do  good  without  the 
help  of  grace. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  man  has  more  power  over  what  is  accord- 
ing to  his  nature  than  over  what  is  beyond  his  nature.  Now 
sin  is  against  his  nature,  as  Damascene  says  {De  Fide  Orthod. 
ji.) ;  whereas  deeds  of  virtue  are  according  to  his  nature, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXI.,  A.  i).  Therefore  since  man  can 
sin  of  himself,  much  more  would  it  seem  that  of  himself  he 
can  wish  and  do  good. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  understanding's  good  is  truth,  as 
the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vi.)  Now  the  intellect  can 
of  itself  know  truth,  even  as  every  other  thing  can  work  its 


327  THK  NECESSITY  OF  (iRACE     Q.  109.  Art.  2 

own  operation  of  itself.     Therefore,  much  more  can  man, 
of  himself,  do  and  wish  good. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  ix.  16):  It  is 
not  of  him  that  willeth  (i.e.,  to  will),  nor  of  him  that  runneth 
(i.e.,  to  run),  hut  of  God  that  showeth  mercy.  And  Augustine 
says  (De  Corrcpt.  et  Gratia,  ii.)  that  without  grace  men  do 
nothing  good  when  they  either  think  or  wish  or  love  or  act. 

I  answer  that,  Man's  nature  may  be  looked  at  in  two  ways : 
first,  in  its  integrity,  as  it  was  in  our  first  parent  before  sin; 
secondly,  as  it  is  corrupted  in  us  after  the  sin  of  our  first 
parent.  Now  in  both  states  human  nature  needs  the  help 
of  ("od  as  First  Mover,  to  do  or  wish  any  good  whatsoever* 
as  stated  above  (A.  i).  But  in  the  state  of  integrity,  as 
regards  the  sufficiency  of  the  operative  power,  man  by  his 
natural  endowments  could  wish  and  do  the  good  propor-' 
tionate  to  his  nature,  such  as  the  good  of  acquired  virtue; 
but  not  surpassing  good,  as  the  good  of  infused  virtue. 
But  in  the  state  of  corrupt  nature,  man  falls  short  of  what 
he  could  do  by  his  nature,  so  that  he  is  unable  to  fulfil  it 
by  his  own  natural  powers.  Yet  because  human  nature^ 
is  not  altogether  corrupted  by  sin,  so  as  to  be  shorn  of  every/ 
natural  good,  even  in  the  state  of  corrupted  nature  it  can,; 
by  virtue  of  its  natural  endowments,  work  some  particular 
good,  as  to  build  dwellings,  plant  vineyards,  and  the  like; 
yet  it  cannot  do  all  the  good  natural  to  it,  so  as  to  fall  short 
in  nothing;  just  as  a  sick  man  can  of  himself  make  some 
movements,  yet  he  cannot  be  perfectly  moved  with  the 
movements  of  one  in  health,  unless  by  the  help  of  medicine 
he  be  cured. 

And   thus  in  the  state  of  perfect  nature  man  needs  a 
gratuitous  strength  superadded  to  natural  strength  for  one 
reason,  viz.,  in  order  to  do  and  wish  supernatural  good;| 
but  for  two  reasons,  in  the  state  of  corrupt  nature,  viz.,  in,l 
order  to  be  healed,  and  furthermore  in  order   to  carry  outf  V 
works  of  supernatural  virtue,  which  are  meritorious.     Be-' 
yond  this,  in  both  states  man  needs  the  Divine  help,  that 
he  may  be  moved  to  act  well. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Man  is  master  of  his  acts  and  of  his  willing 


Q.  109.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  ITHEOLOGICA  '*  328 

or  not  willing,  because  of  his  deliberate  reason,  which  can 
be  bent  to  one  side  or  another.  And  although  he  is  master 
of  his  deliberating  or  not  deliberating,  yet  this  can  only 
be  by  a  previous  deliberation;  and  since  it  cannot  go  on  to 
infinity,  we  must  come  at  length  to  this,  that  man's  free- 
will is  moved  by  an  extrinsic  principle,  which  is  above  the 
human  mind,  to  wit  by  God,  as  the  Philosopher  proves 
in  a  chapter  on  Good  Fortune  (Ethic.  Eudem.  vii.).  Hence 
the  mind  of  man  still  unweakened  is  not  so  much  master  of 
its  act  that  it  does  not  need  to  be  moved  by  God;  and  much 
more  the  free-will  of  man  weakened  by  sin,  whereby  it  is 
hindered  from  good  by  the  corruption  of  the  nature. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  To  sin  is  nothing  else  than  to  fail  in  the  good 
which  belongs  to  any  being  according  to  its  nature.  Now 
as  every  created  thing  has  its  being  from  another,  and, 
considered  in  itself,  is  nothing,  so  does  it  need  to  be  pre- 
served by  another  in  the  good  which  pertains  to  its  nature. 
For  it  can  of  itself  fail  in  good,  even  as  of  itself  it  can  fall 
into  non-existence,  unless  it  is  upheld  by  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Man  cannot  even  know  truth  without 
Divine  help,  as  stated  above  (A.  i) .  And  yet  human  nature 
is  more  corrupt  by  sin  in  regard  to  the  desire  for  good,  than 
in  regard  to  the  knowledge  of  truth. 

Third  Article. 

whether  by  his  own  natural  powers  and  without 
grace  man  can  love  god  above  all  things  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article: — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  without  grace  man  cannot  love 
God  above  all  things  by  his  own  natural  powers.  For  to 
love  God  above  all  things  is  the  proper  and  principal  act  of 
charity.  Now  man  cannot  of  himself  possess  charity, 
since  the  charity  of  God  is  poured  forth  in  our  hearts  by  the 
Holy  Ghost  Who  is  given  to  us,  as  is  said  Rom.  v.  5.  There- 
fore man  by  his  natural  powers  alone  cannot  love  God  above 
all  things. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  no  nature  can  rise  above  itself.     But  to 


329  THE  NECESSITY  OF  GRACE     Q.  109.  Art.  3 

love  God  above  all  things  is  to  tend  above  oneself.  There- 
fore without  the  help  of  grace  no  created  nature  can  love 
God  above  itself. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  to  God,  Who  is  the  Highest  Good,  is 
due  the  best  love,  which  is  that  He  be  loved  above  all  things. 
Now  without  grace  man  is  not  capable  of  giving  God  the 
best  love,  which  is  His  due;  otherwise  it  would  be  useless  to 
add  grace.  Hence  man,  without  grace  and  with  his  natural 
powers  alone,  cannot  love  God  above  all  things. 

On  the  contrary,  As  some  maintain,  man  was  first  made 
with  only  natural  endowments;  and  in  this  state  it  is 
manifest  that  he  loved  God  to  some  extent.  But  he  did 
not  love  God  equally  with  himself,  or  less  than  himself, 
otherwise  he  would  have  sinned.  Therefore  he  loved  God 
above  himself.  Therefore  man,  by  his  natural  powers  alone, 
can  love  God  more  than  himself  and  above  all  things. 

/  answer  that,  As  was  said  above  (P.  i.,  Q.  LX.,  A.  5), 
where  the  various  opinions  concerning  the  natural  love  of 
the  angels  were  set  forth,  man  in  a  state  of  perfect  nature, 
could  by  his  natural  power,  do  the  good  natural  to  him 
without  the  addition  of  any  gratuitous  gift,  though  not 
without  the  help  of  God  moving  him.  Now  to  love  God 
above  all  things  is  natural  to  man  and  to  every  nature, 
not  only  rational  but  irrational,  and  even  to  inanimate  nature 
according  to  the  manner  of  love  which  can  belong  to  each 
creature.  And  the  reason  of  this  is  that  it  is  natural  to  all 
to  seek  and  love  things  according  as  they  are  naturally  fit 
(to  be  sought  and  loved)  since  all  things  act  according  as 
they  are  naturally  fit  as  stated  in  Phys.  ii.  Now  it  is  mani- 
fest that  the  good  of  the  part  is  for  the  good  of  the  whole; 
hence  everything,  by  its  natural  appetite  and  love,  loves 
its  own  proper  good  on  account  of  the  common  good  of  the 
whole  universe,  which  is  God.  Hence  Dionysius  says  {Div. 
Nom.  iv.)  that  God  leads  everything  to  love  of  Himself  .  Hence 
in  the  state  of  perfect  nature  man  referred  the  love  of  him- 
self and  of  all  other  things  to  the  love  of  God  as  to  its  end ; 
and  thus  he  loved  God  more  than  himself  and  above  all 
things.     But  in  the  state  of  corrupt  nature  man  falls  short 


Q.  109.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  330 

of  this  in  the  appetite  of  his  rational  will,  which,  unless  it 
is  cured  by  God's  grace,  follows  its  private  good,  on  account 
of  the  corruption  of  nature.  And  hence  we  must  say  that 
in  the  state  of  perfect  nature  man  did  not  need  the  gift  of 
grace  added  to  his  natural  endowments,  in  order  to  love 
God  above  all  things  naturally,  although  he  needed  God's 
help  to  move  him  to  it;  but  in  the  state  of  corrupt  nature 
man  needs,  even  for  this,  the  help  of  grace  to  heal  his  nature. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Charity  loves  God  above  all  things  in  a 
higher  way  than  nature  does.  For  nature  loves  God  above 
all  things  inasmuch  as  He  is  the  beginning  and  the  end  of 
natural  good;  whereas  charity  loves  Him,  as  He  is  the  object 
of  beatitude,  and  inasmuch  as  man  has  a  spiritual  fellow- 
ship with  God.  Moreover  charity  adds  to  natural  love  of 
God  a  certain  quickness  and  joy,  in  the  same  way  that  every 
habit  of  virtue  adds  to  the  good  act  which  is  done  merely  by 
the  natural  reason  of  a  man  who  has  not  the  habit  of  virtue. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  When  it  is  said  that  nature  cannot  rise  above 
itself,  we  must  not  understand  this  as  if  it  could  not  be  drawn 
to  any  object  above  itself,  for  it  is  clear  that  our  intellect 
by  its  natural  knowledge  can  know  things  above  itself,  as  is 
shown  in  our  natural  knowledge  of  God.  But  we  are  to 
understand  that  nature  cannot  rise  to  an  act  exceeding  the 
proportion  of  its  strength.  Now  to  love  God  above  all 
things  is  not  such  an  act;  for  it  is  natural  to  every  creature, 
as  was  said  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Love  is  said  to  be  best,  both  with  respect  to 
the  degree  of  love,  and  with  regard  to  the  motive  of  loving, 
and  the  mode  of  love.  And  thus  the  highest  degree  of  love 
is  that  whereby  charity  loves  God  as  the  giver  of  beatitude, 
as  was  said  above. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  man  without  grace  and  by  his  own  natural 
powers  can  fulfil  the  commandments  of  the  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article:^ 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man  without  giace,  and  by  his 
own  natural  powers,  can  fulfil  the  commandments  of  the  Law 


331  THE  NECESSITY  OF  GRACE    Q.  109.  Art.  4 

For  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  ii.  14)  that  the  Goitiks  who 
have  not  the  law,  do  by  nature  those  things  that  are  of  the  Law. 
Now  what  a  man  does  naturally  he  can  do  of  himself  without 
grace.  Hence  a  man  can  fuUil  the  commandments  of  the 
Law  without  grace. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Jerome  (Pelagius)  says  in  his  Exposition 
of  the  Catholic  Faith  that  they  are  anathema  who  say  God 
has  laid  impossibilities  upon  man.  Now  what  a  man  cannot 
fulfil  by  himself  is  impossible  to  him.  Therefore  a  man  can 
fulhl  all  the  commandments  of  himself. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  of  all  the  commandments  of  the  Law, 
the  greatest  is  this.  Thou  shall  love  the  Lord  thy  God  with 
thy  whole  heart  (Matth.  xxii.  37).  Now  man  with  his  natural 
endowments  can  fulfil  this  command  by  loving  God  above 
all  things,  as  stated  above  (A.  3) .  Therefore  man  can  fulfil 
all  the  commandments  of  the  Law  without  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Hceres,  Ixxxviii.) 
that  it  is  part  of  the  Pelagian  heresy  that  they  believe  that 
without  grace  man  can  fulfil  all  the  Divine  commandments. 

I  answer  that,  There  are  two  ways  of  fulfilling  the  com- 
mandments of  the  Law. — The  first  regards  the  substance  of 
the  works,  as  when  a  man  does  works  of  justice,  fortitude, 
and  of  other  virtues.  And  in  this  way  man  in  the  state  of 
perfect  nature  could  fulfil  all  the  commandments  of  the  Law; 
otherwise  he  would  have  been  unable  to  sin  in  that  state, 
since  to  sin  is  nothing  else  than  to  transgress  the  Divine 
commandments.  But  in  the  state  of  corrupted  nature  man 
cannot  fulfil  all  the  Divine  commandments  without  healing 
grace.  Secondly,  the  commandments  of  the  law  can  be 
fulfilled  not  merely  as  regards  the  substance  of  the  act,  but 
also  as  regards  the  mode  of  acting,  i.e.,  their  being  done  out 
of  charity.  And  in  this  way,  neither  in  the  state  of  perfect 
nature,  nor  in  the  state  of  corrupt  nature  can  man  fulfil 
the  commandments  of  the  law  without  grace.  Hence, 
Augustine  [De  Corrept.  et  Grat.  ii.)  having  stated  that  without 
grace  men  can  do  no  good  whatever,  adds:  Not  only  do  they 
know  by  its  light  what  to  do,  but  by  its  help  they  do  lovingly 
what  they  know.     Beyond  this,  in  both  states  they  need  the 


Q.  109.  Art.  5    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  332 

help  of  God's  motion  in  order  to  fulfil  the  commandments, 
as  stated  above  (AA.  2,  3). 

Reply  Obj.  i.  As  Augustine  says  {De  Spiv,  et  Lit.  xxvii.), 
do  not  he  disturbed  at  his  saying  that  they  do  by  nature  those 
things  that  are  of  the  Law;  for  the  Spirit  of  grace  works  this, 
in  order  to  restore  in  us  the  image  of  God,  after  which  we  were 
naturally  made. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  What  we  can  do  with  the  Divine  assistance 
is  not  altogether  impossible  to  us;  according  to  the  Phil- 
osopher {Ethic,  iii.) :  What  we  can  do  through  our  friends,  we 
can  do,  in  some  sense,  by  ourselves.  Hence  Jerome  (Pelagius) 
concedes  {ibid.)  that  our  will  is  in  such  a  way  free  that  we 
must  confess  we  still  require  God's  help. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Man  cannot,  with  his  purely  natural  endow- 
ments, fulfil  the  precept  of  the  love  of  God,  as  stated  above 
(A.  3). 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  man  can  merit  everlasting  life  without 

GRACE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  man  can  merit  everlasting  life 
without  grace.  For  Our  Lord  says  (Matth.  xix.  17) :  // 
thou  wilt  enter  into  life,  keep  the  commandments;  from  which 
it  would  seem  that  to  enter  into  everlasting  life  rests  with 
man's  will.  But  what  rests  with  our  will,  we  can  do  of  our- 
selves. Hence  it  seems  that  man  can  merit  everlasting  life 
of  himself. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  eternal  life  is  the  wage  or  reward  bestowed 
by  God  on  men,  according  to  Matth.  v.  12:  Your  reward 
is  very  great  in  heaven.  But  wage  or  reward  is  meted  by 
God  to  everyone  according  to  his  works,  according  to  Ps.  Ixi. 
12:  Thou  wilt  render  to  every  man  according  to  his  works. 
Hence,  since  man  is  master  of  his  works,  it  seems  that  it  is 
within  his  power  to  reach  everlasting  life. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  everlasting  life  is  the  last  end  of  human 
life.  Now  every  natiural  thing  by  its  natural  endowments  can 
attain  its  end.  Much  more,  therefore,  may  man  attain  to 
everlasting  life  by  his  natural  endowments,  without  grace. 


333  THE  NECESSITY  OF  GRACE    Q.  109.  Art.  5 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  vi.  23):  The 
grace  of  God  is  life  everlasting.  And  as  a  gloss  says,  this  is 
said  that  we  may  understand  that  God,  of  His  own  mercy,  leads 
us  to  everlasting  life. 

I  answer  that.  Acts  conducing  to  an  end  must  be  propor- 
tioned to  the  end.  But  no  act  exceeds  the  proportion  of 
its  active  principle;  and  hence  we  see  in  natural  things,  that 
nothing  can  by  its  operation  bring  about  an  effect  which 
exceeds  its  active  force,  but  only  such  as  is  proportionate 
to  its  power.  Now  everlasting  life  is  an  end  exceeding  / 
the  proportion  of  human  nature,  as  is  clear  from  what 
we  have  said  above  (Q.  V.,  A.  5).  Hence  man,  by  his 
natural  endowments,  cannot  produce  meritorious  works 
proportionate  to  everlasting  life;  and  for  this  a  higher 
force  is  needed,  viz.,  the  force  of  grace.  And  thus  without 
grace  man  cannot  merit  everlasting  life;  yet  he  can  per- 
form works  conducing  to  a  good  which  is  natural  to 
man,  as  to  toil  in  the  fields,  to  drink,  to  eat,  or  to  have  friends, 
and  the  like,  as  Augustine  says  (Resp.  contra  Pelag.  iii.  Cf. 
Hypognostic*  iii.). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Man,  by  his  will,  does  works  meritorious  ^ 
of  everlasting  life;  but  as  Augustine  says,  in  the  same  book, 
for  this  it  is  necessary  that  the  will  of  man  should  be  prepared 
with  grace  by  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  As  the  gloss  upon  Rom.  vi.  23,  The  grace 
of  God  is  life  everlasting,  says.  It  is  certain  that  everlasting  life 
is  meted  to  good  works;  but  the  works  to  which  it  is  meted, 
belong  to  God's  grace.  And  it  has  been  said  (A.  4),  that  to 
fulfil  the  commandments  of  the  Law,  in  their  due  way, 
whereby  their  fulfilment  may  be  meritorious,  requires  grace. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  objection  has  to  do  with  the  natural 
end  of  man.  Now  human  nature,  since  it  is  nobler,  can  be 
raised  by  the  help  of  grace  to  a  higher  end,  which  lower 
natures  can  nowise  reach;  even  as  a  man  who  can  recover 
his  health  by  the  help  of  medicines  is  better  disposed  to 
health  than  one  who  can  nowise  recover  it,  as  the  Philosopher 
observes  {De  Coelo  ii.). 

*   To  be  found  among  the  works  of  S.  Augustine. 


Q.  109.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  334 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  a  man,  by  himself  and  without  the  external 
aid  of  grace,  can  prepare  himself  for  grace  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man,  by  himself  and  without 
the  external  help  of  grace,  can  prepare  himself  for  grace. 
For  nothing  impossible  is  laid  upon  man,  as  stated  above 
(A.  4,  ad  i).  But  it  is  written  (Zach.  i.  3) :  Turn  ye  to  Me  .  .  . 
and  I  will  turn  to  you.  Now  to  prepare  for  grace  is  nothing 
more  than  to  turn  to  God.  Therefore  it  seems  that  man 
of  himself,  and  without  the  external  help  of  grace,  can  prepare 
himself  for  grace. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  man  prepares  himself  for  grace  by  doing 
what  is  in  him  to  do,  since  if  man  does  what  is  in  him  to  do 
God  will  not  deny  him  grace,  for  it  is  written  (Matth.  vii.  11) 
that  God  gives  His  good  Spirit  to  them  that  ask  Him.  But 
what  is  in  our  power,  is  in  us  to  do.  Therefore  it  seems  to 
be  in  our  power  to  prepare  ourselves  for  grace. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  a  man  needs  grace  in  order  to  prepare 
for  grace,  with  equal  reason  will  he  need  grace  to  prepare 
himself  for  the  first  grace;  and  thus  to  infinity,  which  is 
impossible.  Hence  it  seems  that  we  must  not  go  beyond 
what  was  said  first,  viz.,  that  man,  of  himself  and  without 
grace,  can  prepare  himself  for  grace. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  it  is  written  (Pro v.  xvi.  i)  that  it  is  the 
part  of  man  to  prepare  the  soul.  Now  an  action  is  said  to 
be  the  part  of  a  man,  when  he  can  do  it  by  himself.  Hence 
it  seems  that  man  by  himself  can  prepare  himself  for 
grace. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (John  vi.  44) :  No  man  can 
come  to  Me  except  the  Father,  Who  hath  sent  Me,  draw  him. 
But  if  man  could  prepare  himself,  he  would  not  need  to  be 
drawn  by  another.  Hence  man  cannot  prepare  himself 
without  the  help  of  grace. 

/  answer  that,  The  preparation  of  the  human  will  for  good 
is  twofold: — the  first,  whereby  it  is  prepared  to  operate 
rightly  and  to  enjoy  God;  and  this  preparation  of  the  will 


335  THE  NFXESSITY  OF  fxRACE     Q.  109.  Art.  6 

cannot  take  place  without  the  habitual  gift  of  grace,  which 
is  the  principle  of  meritorious  works,  as  stated  above  (A.  5). 
There  is  a  second  way  in  which  the  human  will  may  be  taken 
to  be  prepared  for  the  gift  of  habitual  grace  itself.  Now  in  < 
order  that  man  prepare  himself  to  receive  this  gift,  it  is 
not  necessary  to  presuppose  any  further  habitual  gift  in 
the  soul,  otherwise  we  should  go  on  to  infinity.  But  we  ^1^- 
must  presuppose  a  gratuitous  gift  of  God,  Who  moves  the 
soul  inwardly  or  inspires  the  good  wish.  For  in  these  two 
ways  do  we  need  the  Divine  assistance,  as  stated  above 
(AA.  2,  3).  Now  that  we  need  the  help  of  God  to  move  us, 
is  manifest.  For  since  every  agent  acts  for  an  end,  every 
cause  must  direct  its  effect  to  its  end,  and  hence  since  the 
order  of  ends  is  according  to  the  order  of  agents  or  movers, 
man  must  be  directed  to  the  last  end  by  the  motion  of  the 
first  mover,  and  to  the  proximate  end  by  the  motion  of  any 
of  the  subordinate  movers;  as  the  spirit  of  the  soldier  is 
bent  towards  seeking  the  victory  by  the  motion  of  the 
leader  of  the  army — and  towards  following  the  standard 
of  a  regiment  by  the  motion  of  the  standard-bearer.  And 
thus  since  God  is  the  first  Mover  simply,  it  is  by  His  motion 
that  everything  seeks  Him  under  the  common  notion  of 
good,  whereby  everything  seeks  to  be  likened  to  God  in  its 
own  way.  Hence  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Norn,  iv.)  that  God- 
turns  all  to  Himself.  But  He  directs  righteous  men  to 
Himself  as  to  a  special  end,  which  they  seek,  and  to  which 
they  wish  to  cling,  according  to  Ps.  Ixxii.  28,  it  is  good  for 
Me  to  adhere  to  my  God.  And  that  they  are  turned  to  God 
can  only  spring  from  God's  having  turned  them.  Now  to 
prepare  oneself  for  grace  is,  as  it  were,  to  be  turned  to  God ; 
just  as,  whoever  has  his  eyes  turned  away  from  the  light 
of  the  sun,  prepares  himself  to  receive  the  sun's  light,  by 
turning  his  eyes  towards  the  sun.  Hence  it  is  clear  that^ 
man  cannot  prepare  himself  to  receive  the  light  of  grace 
except  by  the  gratuitous  help  of  God  moving  him  inwardly. 
Reply  Ohj.  i.  Man's  turning  to  God  is  by  free-will;  and 
thus  man  is  bidden  to  turn  himself  to  God.  But  free-will  can  ^ 
only  be  turned  to  God,  when  God  turns  it,  according  to 


Q.  109.  Art.  7    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  336 

Jer.  xxxi.  18 :  Convert  me  and  I  shall  he  converted,  for  Thou 
art  the  Lord,  my  God  ;  and  Lament,  v.  21 :  Convert  us,  0  Lord, 
to  Thee,  and  we  shall  he  converted. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Man  can  do  nothing  unless  moved  by  God, 
according  to  John  xv.  5 :  Without  Me,  you  can  do  nothing. 
Hence  when  a  man  is  said  to  do  what  is  in  him  to  do,  this 
is  said  to  be  in  his  power  according  as  he  is  moved  by  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  objection  regards  habitual  grace,  for 
which  some  preparation  is  required,  since  every  form  requires 
a  disposition  in  that  which  is  to  be  its  subject.  But  in  order 
that  man  should  be  moved  by  God,  no  further  motion  is 
presupposed,  since  God  is  the  First  Mover.  Hence  we  need 
not  go  to  infinity. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  It  is  the  part  of  man  to  prepare  his  soul,  since 
he  does  this  by  his  free-will.  And  yet  he  does  npt  do  this 
without  the  help  of  God  moving  him,  and  drawing  him  to 
Himself,  as  was  said  above. 

Seventh  Article, 
whether  man  can  rise  from  sin  without  the  help 

OF   GRACE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  man  can  rise  from  sin  without 
the  help  of  grace.  For  what  is  presupposed  to  grace,  takes 
place  without  grace.  But  to  rise  from  sin  is  presupposed 
to  the  enlightenment  of  grace;  since  it  is  written  (Eph.  v.  14) : 
Arise  from  the  dead  and  Christ  shall  enlighten  thee.  Therefore 
man  can  rise  from  sin  without  grace. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  sin  is  opposed  to  virtue  as  illness  to  health, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXI.,  A.  i  ad  3).  Now,  man,  by  force 
of  his  nature,  can  rise  from  illness  to  health,  without  the 
external  help  of  medicine,  since  there  still  remains  in  him 
the  principle  of  life,  from  which  the  natural  operation 
proceeds.  Hence  it  seems  that,  with  equal  reason,  man 
may  be  restored  by  himself,  and  return  from  the  state  of 
sin  to  the  state  of  justice  without  the  help  of  external  grace. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  every  natural  thing  can  return  by  itself 


337  THE  NECESSITY  OF  GRACE    g.  loy.  Art.  7 

to  the  act  belitting  its  nature,  as  hot  water  returns  by  itself 
to  its  natural  coldness,  and  a  stone  cast  upwards  returns  by 
itself  to  its  natural  movement.  Now  a  sin  is  an  act  against 
nature,  as  is  clear  from  Damascene  [De  hide  Orthod.  ii). 
Hence  it  seems  that  man  by  himself  can  return  from  sin  to 
the  state  of  justice. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Gal.  ii.  21;  cf.  iii.  21): 
For  if  there  had  been  a  law  given  which  could  give  life — then 
Christ  died  in  vain,  i.e.,  to  no  purpose.  Hence  with  equal 
reason,  if  man  has  a  nature,  whereby  he  can  be  justified, 
Christ  died  in  vain,  i.e.,  to  no  purpose.  But  this  cannot 
fittingly  be  said.  Therefore  by  himself  he  cannot  be  j  ustified , 
i.e.,  he  cannot  return  from  a  state  of  sin  to  a  state  of  justice. 

/  answer  that,  Man  by  himself  can  no  wise  rise  from  sin 
without  the  help  of  grace.  For  since  sin  is  transient  as  to  the 
act  and  abiding  in  its  guilt,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXXVH., 
A.  6),  to  rise  from  sin  is  not  the  same  as  to  cease  the  act  of 
sin;  but  to  rise  from  sin  means  that  man  has  restored  to  him 
what  he  lost  by  sinning.  Now  man  incurs  a  triple  loss  by 
sinning,  as  was  clearly  shown  above  (Q.  LXXXV.,  A.  i; 
Q.  LXXXVL,  A.  i;  Q.  LXXXVH. ,  A.  i),  viz.,  stain,  cor- 
ruption of  natural  good,  and  debt  of  punishment.  He  incurs 
a  stain,  inasmuch  as  he  forfeits  the  lustre  of  grace  through 
the  deformity  of  sin.  Natural  good  is  corrupted,  inasmuch  as 
man's  nature  is  disordered  by  man's  will  not  being  subject 
to  God's;  and  this  order  being  overthrown,  the  consequence 
is  that  the  whole  nature  of  sinful  man  remains  disordered. 
Lastly,  there  is  the  debt  of  punishment,  inasmuch  as  by 
sinning  man  deserves  everlasting  damnation. 

Now  it  is  manifest  that  none  of  these  three  can  be  restored 
except  by  God.  For  since  the  lustre  of  grace  springs  from  the 
shedding  of  Divine  light,  this  lustre  cannot  be  brought  back, 
except  God  sheds  His  light  anew:  hence  a  habitual  gift  is 
necessary,  and  this  is  the  light  of  grace.  Likewise,  the  order 
of  nature  can  only  be  restored,  i.e.,  man's  will  can  only  be 
subject  to  God  when  God  draws  man's  will  to  Himself,  as 
stated  above  (A.  6).  So,  too,  the  guilt  of  eternal  punishment 
can  be  remitted  by  God  alone,  against  Whom  the  offence 

11.3  -- 


y.  109.  Art.  7     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  338 

was  committed  and  Who  is  man's  Judge.  And  thus  in  order 
that  man  rise  from  sin  there  is  required  the  help  of  grace, 
both  as  regards  a  habitual  gift,  and  as  regards  the  internal 
motion  of  God. 

Reply  Obj,  1.  To  man  is  bidden  that  which  pertains  to 
the  act  of  free-will,  as  this  act  is  required  in  order  that  man 
should  rise  from  sin.  Hence  when  it  is  said,  Arise,  and 
Christ  shall  enlighten  thee,  we  are  not  to  think  that  the  com- 
plete rising  from  sin  precedes  the  enlightenment  of  grace; 
but  that  when  man  by  his  free-will,  moved  by  God,  strives 
to  rise  from  sin,  he  receives  the  light  of  justifying  grace. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  natural  reason  is  not  the  sufficient 
principle  of  the  health  that  is  in  man  by  justifying  grace. 
This  principle  is  grace  which  is  taken  away  by  sin.  Hence 
man  cannot  be  restored  by  himself;  but  he  requires  the  lights 
of  grace  to  be  poured  upon  him  anew,  as  if  the  soul  were 
infused  into  a  dead  body  for  its  resurrection. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  When  nature  is  perfect,  it  can  be  restored 
by  itself  to  its  befitting  and  proportionate  condition;  but 
without  exterior  help  it  cannot  be  restored  to  what  sur- 
passes its  measure.  And  thus  human  nature  undone  by 
reason  of  the  act  of  sin,  remains  no  longer  perfect,  but  cor- 
rupted, as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXXV.) ;  nor  can  it  be  restored, 
by  itself,  to  its  connatural  good,  much  less  to  the  super- 
natural good  of  justice. 

Eighth  Article, 
whether  man  without  grace  can  avoid  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  without  grace  man  can  avoid 
sin.  Because  no  one  sins  in  what  he  cannot  avoid,  as 
Augustine  says  [De  Ditab.  Anim.  x.,  xi.;  De  Libero  Arbit.  iii.). 
Hence  if  a  man  in  mortal  sin  cannot  avoid  sin,  it  would  seem 
that  in  sinning  he  does  not  sin,  which  is  impossible. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  men  are  corrected  that  they  may  not 
sin.  If  therefore  a  man  in  mortal  sin  cannot  avoid  sin, 
correction  would  seem  to  be  given  to  no  purpose;  which  is 
absurd. 


339  THE  NECESSITY  OF  GRACE     Q.  109.  Art.  8 

Obj.  3.  Further,  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  xv.  18) :  Before  man 
is  life  and  death,  good  and  evil;  that  which  he  shall  choose  shall 
be  given  him.  But  by  sinning  no  one  ceases  to  be  a  man. 
Hence  it  is  still  in  his  power  to  choose  good  or  evil;  and 
thus  man  can  avoid  sin  without  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Perfect  Jnst.  xxi.) : 
Whoever  denies  that  we  ought  to  say  the  prayer  Lead  us  not 
into  temptation  [and  they  deny  it  who  maintain  that  the  help 
of  God's  grace  is  not  necessary  to  man  for  salvation,  but  that 
the  gift  of  the  law  is  enough  for  the  human  will)  ought  without 
doubt  to  be  removed  beyond  all  hearing,  and  to  be  anathemc.tized 
by  the  tongues  of  all. 

I  answer  that,  We  may  speak  of  man  in  two  ways:  first,  in 
the  state  of  perfect  nature ;  secondly,  in  the  state  of  corrupted 
nature.  Now  in  the  state  of  perfect  nature,  man,  without 
habitual  grace,  could  avoid  sinning  either  mortally  or  venially ; 
since  to  sin  is  nothing  else  than  to  stray  from  what  is  accord- 
ing to  our  nature. — and  in  the  state  of  perfect  nature  man 
could  avoid  this.  Nevertheless  he  could  not  have  done  it 
without  God's  help  to  uphold  him  in  good,  since  if  this  had 
been  withdrawn,  even  his  nature  would  have  fallen  back  into 
nothingness. 

But  in  the  state  of  corrupt  nature  man  needs  grace  to 
heal  his  nature  in  order  that  he  may  entirely  abstain  from 
sin.  And  in  the  present  life  this  healing  is  wrought  in  the 
mind, — the  carnal  appetite  being  not  yet  restored.  Hence 
the  Apostle  (Rom.  vii.  25)  says  in  the  person  of  one  who  is 
restored:  /  myself,  with  the  m^nd,  serve  the  law  of  God,  but 
with  the  flesh,  the  law  of  sin.  And  in  this  state  man  caii 
abstain  from  all  mortal  sin,  which  takes  its  stand  in  his 
reason,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXIV.  A.  5);  but  man  cannot 
abstain  from  all  venial  sin  on  account  of  the  corruption 
of  his  lower  appetite  of  sensuality.  For  man  can,  indeed, 
repress  each  of  its  movements  (and  hence  they  are  sinfu 
and  voluntary),  but  not  all,  because  whilst  he  is  resisting 
one,  another  may  arise,  and  also  because  the  reason  is  not 
always  alert  to  avoid  these  movements,  as  was  said  above 
(Q.LXXIY.,  A.  3,  ad  2). 

So,  too,  before  man's  reason,  wherein  is  mortal  sin,  is 


Q.  109.  Art.  8    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  340 

restored  by  justifying  grace,  he  can  avoid  each  mortal 
sin,  and  for  a  time,  since  it  is  not  necessary  that  he  should  be 
always  actually  sinning.  But  it  cannot  be  that  he  remains 
for  a  long  time  without  mortal  sin.  Hence  Gregory  says 
[Super  Ezech.  Norn,  xi.)  that  a  sin  not  at  once  taken  away  by 
repentance,  by  its  weight  drags  us  down  to  other  sins  :  and  this 
because,  as  the  lower  appetite  ought  to  be  subject  to  the 
reason,  so  should  the  reason  be  subject  to  God,  and  should 
place  in  Him  the  end  of  its  will.  Now  it  is  by  the  end  that 
all  human  acts  ought  to  be  regulated,  even  as  it  is  by  the 
judgment  of  the  reason  that  the  movements  of  the  lower 
appetite  should  be  regulated.  And  thus,  even  as  inordinate 
movements  of  the  sensitive  appetite  cannot  help  occurring 
since  the  lower  appetite  is  not  subject  to  reason,  so  likewise, 
since  man's  reason  is  not  entirely  subject  to  God,  the  con- 
sequence is  that  many  disorders  occur  in  the  reason.  For 
when  man's  heart  is  not  so  fixed  on  God  as  to  be  unwilling 
to  be  parted  from  Him  for  the  sake  of  finding  any  good  or 
avoiding  any  evil,  many  things  happen  for  the  achieving 
or  avoiding  of  which  a  man  strays  from  God  and  breaks 
His  commandments,  and  thus  sins  mortally :  especially  since, 
when  surprised,  a  man  acts  according  to  his  preconceived 
end  and  his  pre-existing  habits,  as  the  Philosopher  says 
(Ethic,  iii.) ;  although  with  premeditation  of  his  reason  a 
man  may  do  something  outside  the  order  of  his  preconceived 
end  and  the  inclination  of  his  habit.  But  because  a  man 
cannot  always  have  this  premeditation,  it  cannot  help 
occurring  that  he  acts  in  accordance  with  his  will  turned 
aside  from  God,  unless,  by  grace,  he  is  quickly  brought  back 
to  the  due  order. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Man  can  avoid  each  but  not  every  act  of 
sin,  except  by  grace,  as  stated  above.  Nevertheless,  since 
it  is  by  his  own  shortcoming  that  he  does  not  prepare  him- 
self to  have  grace,  the  fact  that  he  cannot  avoid  sin  without 
grace  does  not  excuse  him  from  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Correction  is  useful  in  order  that  out  of  the 
sorrow  of  correction  may  spring  the  wish  to  be  regenerate ; 
if  indeed  he  who  is  corrected  is  a  son  of  promise,  in  such  sort 


341  THE  NECESSITY  OF  GRACE    Q.  ioq.  Art.  q 

that  whilst  the  noise  of  correction  is  outivardly  resounding  and 
punishing,  God  by  hidden  inspirations  is  inwardly  causing  him 
to  will,  as  Augustine  says  [De  Corr.  et  Grat  a  vi.).  Correction 
is  therefore  necessary,  from  the  fact  that  man's  will  is  required 
in  order  to  abstain  from  sin ;  yet  it  is  not  sufficient  without 
God's  help.  Hence  it  is  written  (Eccles.  vii.  14) :  Consider 
the  works  of  God  that  no  man  can  correct  whom  He  hath  despised. 
Reply  Obj.  3.  As  Augustine  says  (Hyfognostic  iii.),  this 
saying  is  to  be  understood  of  man  in  the  state  of  perfect 
nature,  when  as  yet  he  was  not  a  slave  of  sin.  Hence  he  was 
able  to  sin  and  not  to  sin.  Now,  too,  whatever  a  man  wills, 
is  given  to  him ;  but  his  willing  good,  he  has  by  God's  assist- 
ance. 

Ninth  Article. 

whether  one  who  has  already  obtained  grace,  can, 
of  himself  and  without  further  help  of  grace, 
do  good  and  avoid  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Ninth  Article: — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  whoever  has  already  obtained 
grace,  can  by  himself  and  without  further  help  of  grace,  do 
good  and  avoid  sin.  For  a  thing  is  useless  or  imperfect,  if 
it  does  not  fulfil  what  it  was  given  for.  Now  grace  is  given 
to  us  that  w^e  may  do  good  and  keep  from  sin.  Hence  if 
with  grace  man  cannot  do  this,  it  seems  that  grace  is  either 
useless  or  imperfect. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  by  grace  the  Holy  Spirit  dwells  in  us 
according  to  i  Cor.  iii.  16:  Know  you  not  that  you  are  the 
temple  of  God,  and  that  the  Spirit  of  God  dwelleth  in  you  ?  Now 
since  the  Spirit  of  God  is  omnipotent,  He  is  sufficient  to 
ensure  our  doing  good  and  to  keep  us  from  sin.  Hence  a 
man  who  has  obtained  grace  can  do  the  above  two  things 
without  any  further  assistance  of  grace. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  if  a  man  who  has  obtained  grace  needs 
further  aid  of  grace  in  order  to  live  righteously  and  to  keep 
free  from  sin,  with  equal  reason,  will  he  need  yet  another 
grace,  even  though  he  has  obtained  this  first  help  of  grace. 
Therefore  we  must  go  on  to  infmity;  which  is  impossible. 


Q.  109.  Art.  9      THE  ''  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  342 

Hence  whoever  is  in  grace  needs  no  further  help  of  grace  in 
order  to  do  righteously  and  to  keep  free  from  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [De  Natura  et  Gratia,  xxvi.) 
that  as  the  eye  of  the  body  though  most  healthy  cannot  see 
unless  it  is  helped  by  the  brightness  of  light,  so,  neither  can  a 
man,  even  if  he  is  most  righteous,  live  righteously  unless  he 
be  helped  by  the  eternal  light  of  justice.  But  justification  is 
by  grace,  according  to  Rom.  iii.  24:  Being  justified  freely  by 
His  grace.  Hence  even  a  man  who  already  possesses  grace 
needs  a  further  assistance  of  grace  in  order  to  live  righteously. 
^\  g  /  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  5),  in  order  to  live 
righteously  a  man  needs  a  twofold  help  of  God — first,  a 
habitual  gift  whereby  corrupted  human  nature  is  healed, 
and  after  being  healed  is  lifted  up  so  as  to  work  deeds 
meritorious  of  everlasting  life,  which  exceed  the  capability 
of  nature.  Secondly,  man  needs  the  help  of  grace  in  order 
to  be  moved  by  God  to  act. 
"^ '  Now  with  regard  to  the  first  kind  of  help,  man  does  not 
need  a  further  help  of  grace,  e.g.,  a  further  infused  habit. 
Yet  he  needs  the  help  of  grace  in  another  way,  i.e.,  in  order 
to  be  moved  by  God  to  act  righteously,  and  this  for  two 
reasons:  first,  for  the  general  reason  that  no  created  thing 
can  put  forth  any  act,  unless  by  virtue  of  the  Divine  motion. 
vSecondly,  for  this  special  reason — the  condition  of  the  state 
of  human  nature.  For  although  healed  by  grace  as  to  the 
mind,  yet  it  remains  corrupted  and  poisoned  in  the  flesh, 
whereby  it  serves  the  law  of  sin,  Rom.  vii.  25.  In  the  intel- 
lect, too,  there  remains  the  darkness  of  ignorance,  whereby, 
as  is  written  (Rom.  viii.  26) :  We  know  not  what  we  should 
pray  for  as  we  ought;  since  on  account  of  the  various  turns 
of  circumstances,  and  because  we  do  not  know  ourselves 
perfectly,  we  cannot  fully  know  what  is  for  our  good,  accord- 
ing to  Wis.  ix.  14 :  For  the  thoughts  of  mortal  men  are  fearful 
and  our  counsels  uncertain.  Hence  we  must  be  guided  and 
guarded  by  God,  Who  knows  and  can  do  all  things.  For 
which  reason  also  it  is  becoming  in  those  who  have  been 
born  again  as  sons  of  God,  to  say:  Lead  us  not  into  temptation^ 
and  Thy  Will  be  done  on  earth  as  it  is  in  heaven,  and  what- 


343  THE  NECESSITY  OF  GRACE      Q.  109.  Art.  10 

ever  else  is  contained  in  the  Lord's  Prayer  pertaining 
to  this. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  gift  of  habitual  grace  is  not  therefore 
given  to  us  that  we  may  no  longer  need  the  Divine  help;  for 
every  creature  needs  to  be  preserved  in  the  good  received  from 
Him.  Hence  if  after  having  received  grace  man  still  needs 
the  Divine  help,  it  cannot  be  concluded  that  grace  is  given  to 
no  purpose,  or  that  it  is  imperfect,  since  man  will  need  the 
Divine  help  even  in  the  state  of  glory,  when  grace  shall  be 
fully  perfected.  But  here  grace  is  to  some  extent  imperfect, 
inasmuch  as  it  does  not  completely  heal  man,  as  stated 
above. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  operation  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  which 
moves  and  protects,  is  not  circumscribed  by  the  effect  of 
habitual  grace  which  it  causes  in  us;  but  beyond  this 
effect  He,  together  with  the  Father  and  the  Son,  moves  and 
protects  us. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  argument  merely  proves  that  man 
needs  no  further  habitual  grace. 

Tenth  Article. 

whether  man  possessed  of  grace  needs  the  help  of 
grace  in  order  to  persevere  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Tenth  Article: — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  man  possessed  of  grace  needs 
no  help  of  grace  to  persevere.  For  perseverance  is  some- 
thing less  than  virtue,  even  as  continence  is,  as  is  clear 
from  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  vii.).  Now  since  man  is 
justified  by  grace,  he  needs  no  further  help  of  grace  in  order 
to  have  the  virtues.  Much  less,  therefore,  does  he  need  the 
help  of  grace  to  have  perseverance. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  all  the  virtues  are  infused  at  once.  But 
perseverance  is  put  down  as  a  virtue.  Hence  it  seems 
that,  together  with  grace,  perseverance  is  given  to  the  other 
infused  virtues. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  as  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  v.  20)  more 
was  restored   to  man  by  Christ's  gift,  than  he  had  lost 


Q.  109.  Art.  10     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  344 

by  Adam's  sin.  But  Adam  received  what  enabled  him  to 
persevere;  and  thus  man  docs  not  need  grace  in  order  to 
persevere. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Persev.  ii.) :  Why  is 
perseverance  besought  of  God,  if  it  is  not  bestowed  by  God  ? 
For  is  it  not  a  mocking  request  to  seek  what  we  know  He  does 
not  give,  and  what  is  in  our  power  without  His  giving  it  ? 
Now  perseverance  is  besought  by  even  those  who  arc 
hallowed  by  grace ;  and  this  is  seen,  when  we  say  Hallowed 
be  Thy  name,  which  Augustine  confirms  by  the  words  of 
Cyprian  (De  Correp.  et  Grat.  xii.).  Hence  man,  even  when 
possessed  of  grace,  needs  perseverance  to  be  given  to  him  by 
God. 

I  answer  that,  Perseverance  is  taken  in  three  ways.  First, 
to  signify  a  habit  of  the  mind  whereby  a  man  stands  stead- 
fastly, lest  he  be  moved  by  the  assault  of  sadness  from  what 
is  virtuous.  And  thus  perseverance  is  to  sadness  as  con- 
tinence is  to  concupiscence  and  pleasure,  as  the  Philosopher 
says  {Ethic,  vii.).  Secondly,  perseverance  may  be  called 
a  habit,  whereby  a  man  has  the  purpose  of  persevering  in 
good  unto  the  end.  And  in  both  these  ways  perseverance  is 
infused  together  with  grace,  even  as  continence  and  the  other 
virtues  are.  Thirdly,  perseverance  is  called  the  abiding 
in  good  to  the  end  of  life.  And  in  order  to  have  this  perse- 
verance man  does  not,  indeed,  need  another  habitual  grace, 
but  he  needs  the  Divine  assistance  guiding  and  guarding 
him  against  the  attacks  of  the  passions,  as  appears  from 
the  preceding  article.  And  hence  after  anyone  has  been 
justified  by  grace,  he  still  needs  to  beseech  God  for  the 
aforesaid  gift  of  perseverance,  that  he  may  be  kept  from 
evil  till  the  end  of  his  life.  For  to  many  grace  is  given  to 
whom  perseverance  in  grace  is  not  given. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  This  objection  regards  the  first  mode  of 
perseverance,  as  the  second  objection  regards  the  second. 

Hence  the  solution  of  the  second  objection  is  clear. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  Augustine,  says  {DeNatura  et  Gratia,  xliii. 
Cf.  De  Correp.  et  Grat.  xii.)  in  the  original  state  man  received 
a  gift  whereby  he  could  persevere,  but  to  persevere  was  not  given 


345  THE  NECESSITY  OE  GRACE     Q.  109.  Art.  10 

him.  But  now,  by  the  grace  of  Christ,  many  receive  both  the 
gift  of  grace  whereby  they  may  persevere,  and  the  further  gift 
of  'persevering,  and  thus  Christ's  gift  is  greater  than  Adam's 
fault.  Nevertheless  it  was  easier  for  man  to  persevere, 
with  the  gift  of  grace  in  the  state  of  innocence  in  which 
the  flesh  was  not  rebellious  against  the  spirit,  than  it  is 
now.  For  the  restoration  by  Christ's  grace,  although  it 
is  already  begun  in  the  mind,  is  not  yet  completed  in  the 
flesh,  as  it  will  be  in  heaven,  where  man  will  not  merely  be 
able  to  persevere  but  will  be  unable  to  sin. 


QUESTION   ex. 

OF  THE  GRACE  OF  GOD  AS  REGARDS  ITS  ESSENCE. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  grace  of  God  as  regards  its 
essence ;  and  under  this  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry : 
(i)  Whether  grace  implies  something  in  the  soul  ?  (2) 
Whether  grace  is  a  quality  ?  (3)  Whether  grace  differs 
from  infused  virtue  ?     (4)  Of  the  subject  of  grace. 

First  Article, 
whether  grace  implies  anything  in  the  soul  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article: — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  grace  does  not  imply  any- 
thing in  the  soul.  For  man  is  said  to  have  the  grace  of  God 
even  as  the  grace  of  man.  Hence  it  is  written  (Gen.  xxxix. 
21)  that  the  Lord  gave  to  Joseph  favour  (gratiam)  in  the 
sight  of  the  chief  keeper  of  the  prison.  Now  when  we  say  that 
a  man  has  the  favour  of  another,  nothing  is  implied  in 
him  who  has  the  favour  of  the  other,  but  an  acceptance  is 
implied  in  him  whose  favour  he  has.  Hence  when  we, 
say  that  a  man  has  the  grace  of  God,  nothing  is  impUed 
in  his  soul;  but  we  merely  signify  the  Divine  acceptance. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  as  the  soul  quickens  the  body  so  does 
God  quicken  the  soul;  hence  it  is  written  (Deut.  xxx.  20): 
He  is  thy  life.  Now  the  soul  quickens  the  body  immediately. 
Therefore  nothing  can  come  as  a  medium  between  God 
and  the  soul.  Hence  grace  implies  nothing  created  in  the 
soul. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  on  Rom.  i.  7,  Grace  to  you  and  peace,  the 

346 


347  THE  GRACE  OF  GOD         Q.  no.  Art.  i 

gloss  says:  Grace,  i.e.,  the  remission  of  sins.  Now  the  remis- 
sion of  sin  implies  nothing  in  the  soul,  but  only  in  Ciod, 
Who  does  not  impute  the  sin,  according  to  Ps.  xxxi.  2: 
Blessed  is  the  man  to  whom  the  Lord  hath  not  imputed  sin. 
Hence  neither  does  grace  imply  anything  in  the  soul. 

On  the  contrary,  Light  implies  something  in  what  is  enligh- 
tened. But  grace  is  a  light  of  the  soul;  hence  Augustine 
says  [De  Natura  et  Gratia  xxii.) :  The  light  of  truth  rightly 
deserts  the  prevaricator  of  the  law,  and  those  who  have  been  thus 
deserted  become  blind.  Therefore  grace  implies  something 
in  the  soul. 

I  answer  that,  According  to  the  common  manner  of  speech, 
grace  is  usually  taken  in  three  ways,  First,  for  anyone's  love, 
as  we  are  accustomed  to  say  that  the  soldier  is  in  the  good 
graces  of  the  king,  i.e.,  the  king  looks  on  him  with  favour. 
Secondly,  it  is  taken  for  any  gift  freely  bestowed,  as  we  are 
accustomed  to  say:  I  do  you  this  act  of  grace.  Thirdly, 
it  is  taken  for  the  recompense  of  a  gift  given  gratis,  inasmuch 
as  we  are  said  to  be  grateful  for  benefits.  Of  these  three 
the  second  depends  on  the  first,  since  one  bestows  something 
on  another  gratis  from  the  love  wherewith  he  receives  him 
into  his  good  graces.  And  from  the  second  proceeds  the 
third,  since  from  benefits  bestowed  gratis  arises  gratitude. 

Now  as  regards  the  last  two,  it  is  clear  that  grace  implies 
something  in  him  who  receives  grace:  first,  the  gift  given 
gratis;  secondly,  the  acknowledgement  of  the  gift.  But  as 
regards  the  first,  a  difference  must  be  noted  between  the 
grace  of  God  and  the  grace  of  man;  for  since  the  creature's 
good  springs  from  the  Divine  will,  some  good  in  the  creature 
flows  from  God's  love,  whereby  He  wishes  the  good  of  the 
creature.  On  the  other  hand,  the  will  of  man  is  moved  by 
the  good  pre-existing  in  things ;  and  hence  man's  love  does 
not  wholly  cause  the  good  of  the  thing,  but  pre-supposes 
it  either  in  part  or  wholly.  Therefore  it  is  clear  that  every 
love  of  God  is  followed  at  some  time  by  a  good  caused  in 
the  creature,  but  not  co-eternal  with  the  eternal  love. 
And  according  to  this  difference  of  good  the  love  of  God 
to  the  creature  is  looked  at  differently.     For  one  is  common, 


Q.  no.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  348 

whereby  He  loves  all  things  that  arc  (Wis.  xi.  25),  and  thereby 
gives  things  their  natural  being.  But  the  second  is  a 
special  love,  whereby  He  draws  the  rational  creature  above 
the  condition  of  its  nature  to  a  participation  of  the  Divine 
good;  and  according  to  this  love  He  is  said  to  love  anyone 
simply,  since  it  is  by  this  love  that  God  simply  wishes  the 
eternal  good,  which  is  Himself,  for  the  creature. 

Accordingly  when  a  man  is  said  to  have  the  grace  of  God, 
there  is  signified  something  bestowed  on  man  by  God. 
Nevertheless  the  grace  of  God  sometimes  signifies  God's 
eternal  love,  as  we  say  the  grace  of  predestination,  inasmuch 
as  God  gratuitously  and  not  from  merits  predestines  or 
elects  some;  for  it  is  written  (Eph.  i.  5):  He  hath  predesti- 
nated us  into  the  adoption  of  children  .  .  .  unto  the  praise  of 
the  glory  of  His  grace. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Even  when  a  man  is  said  to  be  in  another's 
good  graces,  it  is  understood  that  there  is  something  in  him 
pleasing  to  the  other;  even  as  anyone  is  said  to  have  God's 
grace — with  this  difference,  that  what  is  pleasing  to  a  man  in 
another  is  presupposed  to  his  love,  but  whatever  is  pleasing 
to  God  in  a  man  is  caused  by  the  Divine  love,  as  was  said 
above. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  God  is  the  life  of  the  soul  after  the  manner 
of  an  efficient  cause;  but  the  soul  is  the  life  of  the  body 
after  the  manner  of  a  formal  cause.  Now  there  is  no 
medium  between  form  and  matter,  since  the  form,  of  itself, 
informs  the  matter  or  subject;  whereas  the  agent  informs  the 
subject,  not  by  its  substance,  but  by  the  form,  which  it 
causes  in  the  matter. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Augustine  says  {Retract,  i.) :  When  I  said 
that  grace  was  for  the  remission  of  sins,  and  peace  for  our 
reconciliation  with  God,  you  must  not  take  it  to  mean  that 
peace  and  reconciliation  do  not  pertain  to  general  grace,  but 
that  the  special  name  of  grace  signifies  the  remission  of  sins. 
Not  only  grace,  therefore,  but  many  other  of  God's  gifts 
pertain  to  grace.  And  hence  the  remission  of  sins  does  not 
take  place  without  some  effect  divinely  caused  in  us,  as  will 
appear  later  (Q.  CXIII.,  A.  2). 


349  THE  GRACE  OF  GOD  Q.  no.  Art.  2 


Second  Article, 
whether  grace  is  a  quality  of  the  soul  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  grace  is  not  a  quality  of 
the  soul.  For  no  quality  acts  on  its  subject,  since  the 
action  of  a  quality  is  not  without  the  action  of  its  subject, 
and  thus  the  subject  would  necessarily  act  upon  itself. 
But  grace  acts  upon  the  soul,  by  justifying  it.  Therefore 
grace  is  not  a  quality. 

Ohj.  2.  Furthermore,  substance  is  nobler  than  quality. 
But  grace  is  nobler  than  the  nature  of  the  soul,  since  we 
can  do  many  things  by  grace,  to  which  nature  is  not  equal, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  CIX.,  AA.  i,  2,  3).  Therefore  grace  is 
not  a  quality. 

Ohj.  3.  Furthermore,  no  quality  remains  after  it  has 
ceased  to  be  in  its  subject.  But  grace  remains;  since  it  is 
not  corrupted,  for  thus  it  would  be  reduced  to  nothing,  since 
it  was  created  from  nothing,  hence  it  is  called  a  new  creature 
(Gal.  vi.  15). 

On  the  contrary,  on  Ps.  ciii.  15,  That  he  may  make  the 
face  cheerful  with  oil ;  the  gloss  says :  Grace  is  a  certain 
beauty  of  soul,  which  wins  the  Divine  love.  But  beauty  of 
soul  is  a  quality,  even  as  beauty  of  body.  Therefore  grace 
is  a  quality. 

/  answer  that,  as  stated  above  (A.  i),  there  is  under- 
stood to  be  an  effect  of  God's  gratuitous  will  in  whoever 
is  said  to  have  God's  grace.  Now  it  was  stated  (Q.  CIX., 
A.  i)  that  man  is  aided  by  God's  gratuitous  will  in  two 
ways: — First,  inasmuch  as  man's  soul  is  moved  by  God  to 
know  or  will  or  do  something,  and  in  this  way  the  gratuitous 
effect  in  man  is  not  a  quality,  but  a  movement  of  the  soul ; 
for  motion  is  the  act  of  the  mover  in  the  moved.  Secondly, 
man  is  helped  by  God's  gratuitous  will,  inasmuch  as  a 
habitual  gift  is  infused  by  God  into  the  soul;  and  for  this 
reason,  that  it  is  not  fitting  that  God  should  provide  less 
for  those  He  loves,   that  they  may  acquire  supernatuial 


Q.  no.  Art.  2      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  350 

good,  than  for  creatures,  whom  He  loves  that  they  may 
acquire  natural  good.  Now  He  so  provides  for  natural 
creatures,  that  not  merely  does  He  move  them  to  their 
natural  acts,  but  He  bestows  upon  them  certain  forms  and 
powers,  which  are  the  principles  of  acts,  in  order  that  they 
may  of  themselves  be  inclined  to  these  movements,  and 
thus  the  movements  whereby  they  are  moved  by  God 
become  natural  and  easy  to  creatures,  according  to 
Wis.  viii.  i:  she  .  .  .  ordereth  all  things  sweetly.  Much  more 
therefore  does  He  infuse  into  such  as  He  moves  towards 
the  acquisition  of  supernatural  good,  certain  forms  or 
supernatural  qualities,  whereby  they  may  be  moved  by  Him 
sweetly  and  promptly  ^o  acquire  eternal  good ;  and  thus  the 
gift  of  grace  is  a  quality. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Grace,  as  a  quality,  is  said  to  act  upon  the 
soul,  not  after  the  manner  of  an  efficient  cause,  but  after 
the  manner  of  a  formal  cause,  as  whiteness  makes  a  thing 
white,  and  justice,  just. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Every  substance  is  either  the  nature  of  the 
thing  whereof  it  is  the  substance,  or  is  a  part  of  the  nature, 
even  as  matter  and  form  are  called  substance.  And  because 
grace  is  above  human  nature,  it  cannot  be  a  substance  or  a 
substantial  form,  but  is  an  accidental  form  of  the  soul. 
Now  what  is  substantially  in  God,  becomes  accidental  in  the 
soul  participating  the  Divine  goodness,  as  is  clear  in  the 
case  of  knowledge.  And  thus  because  the  soul  participates 
in  the  Divine  goodness  imperfectly,  the  participation  of 
the  Divine  goodness,  which  is  grace,  has  its  being  in  the 
soul  in  a  less  perfect  way  than  the  soul  subsists  in  itself. 
Nevertheless,  inasmuch  as  it  is  the  expression  or  participa- 
tion of  the  Divine  goodness,  it  is  nobler  than  the  nature  of 
the  soul,  though  not  in  its  mode  of  being 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  Boethius  (pseudo-Beda)  says  [Sentent. 
Philosoph.  ex  AristoL),  the  being  of  an  accident  is  to  inhere. 
Hence  no  accident  is  called  being  as  if  it  had  being,  but 
because  by  it  something  is;  hence  it  is  said  to  belong  to 
a  being  rather  than  to  be  a  being  (Metaph.  vii.).  And 
because  to  become  and  to  be  corrupted  belong  to  what  is, 


351  THE  GRACE  OF  GOD  Q.  no.  Art.  3 

properly  speaking  no  accident  comes  into  being  or  is  cor- 
rupted, but  is  said  to  come  into  being  and  to  be  corrupted 
inasmuch  as  its  subject  begins  or  ceases  to  be  in  act  with 
this  accident.  And  thus  grace  is  also  said  to  be  created 
inasmuch  as  men  are  created  with  reference  to  it,  i.e.,  are 
given  a  new  being  out  of  nothing,  i.e.,  not  from  merits, 
according  to  Eph.  ii.  10,  created  in  Jesus  Christ  in  good  works. 

Third  Article, 
whether  grace  is  the  same  as  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  grace  is  the  same  as  virtue. 
For  Augustine  says  [De  Spir.  et  Litt.  xiv.)  that  operating 
grace  is  faith  that  worketh  by  charity.  But  faith  that  worketh 
by  charity  is  a  virtue.     Therefore  grace  is  a  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  what  fits  the  definition,  fits  the  defined. 
But  the  definitions  of  virtue  given  by  saints  and  philosophers 
fit  grace,  since  it  makes  its  subject  good,  and  his  work  good, 
and  it  is  a  good  quality  of  the  mind,  whereby  we  live  righteously 
etc.     Therefore  grace  is  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  grace  is  a  quality.  Now  it  is  clearly  not 
in  the  fourth  species  of  quality;  viz.  form  which  is  the  abiding 
figure  of  things,  since  it  does  not  belong  to  bodies.  Nor  is  it 
in  the  third,  since  it  is  not  a  passion  nor  a  passion-like 
quality,  which  is  in  the  sensitive  part  of  the  soul,  as  is 
proved  in  Physic,  viii. ;  and  grace  is  principally  in  the  mind. 
Nor  is  it  in  the  second  species,  which  is  natural  power  or 
impotence  ;  since  grace  is  above  nature  and  does  not  regard 
good  and  evil,  as  does  natural  power.  Therefore  it  must 
be  in  the  first  species  which  is  habit  or  disposition.  Now 
habits  of  the  mind  are  virtues;  since  even  knowledge  itself 
is  a  virtue  after  a  manner,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LVIL, 
AA.  I,  2).     Therefore  grace  is  the  same  as  virtue. 

On  the  contrary.  If  grace  is  virtue,  it  would  seem  before  all 
to  be  one  of  the  three  theological  virtues.  But  grace  is 
neither  faith  nor  hope,  for  these  can  be  without  sanctifying 
grace.     Nor  is  it  charity,  since  grace  foreruns  charity,  as 


Q.  no.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  352 

Augustine  says  in  his  book  on  the  Predestination  of  the 
Saints  [Do  Bono  Persev.  xvi.).  Therefore  grace  is  not 
virtue. 

/  answer  that,  Some  held  that  grace  and  virtue  were 
identical  in  essence,  and  differed  only  logically, — in  the 
sense  that  we  speak  of  grace  inasmuch  as  it  makes  man 
pleasing  to  God,  or  is  given  gratuitously; — and  of  virtue 
inasmuch  as  it  empowers  us  to  act  rightly.  And  the  Master 
seems  to  have  thought  this  (2  Sent.,  Dist  27). 

But  if  anyone  rightly  considers  the  nature  of  virtue, 
this  cannot  hold,  since,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (Physic,  vii.), 
virtue  is  a  disposition  of  what  is  perfect, — and  I  call  perfect 
what  is  disposed  according  to  its  nature.  Now  from  this  it  is 
clear  that  the  virtue  of  a  thing  has  reference  to  some  pre- 
existing nature,  from  the  fact  that  everything  is  disposed 
with  reference  to  what  befits  its  nature.  But  it  is  manifest 
that  the  virtues  acquired  by  human  acts  of  which  we  spoke 
above  (Q.  LV.,  seqq.)  are  dispositions,  whereby  a  man  is 
fittingly  disposed  with  reference  to  the  nature  whereby  he 
is  a  man ;  whereas  infused  virtues  dispose  man  in  a  higher 
manner  and  towards  a  higher  end,  and  consequently  in  relation 
to  some  higher  nature,  i.e.,  in  relation  to  a  participation  of 
the  Divine  Nature,  according  to  2  Pet.  i.  4:  He  hath  given 
us  most  great  and  most  precious  promises  ;  that  by  these  you 
may  he  made  partakers  of  the  Divine  Nature.  And  it  is  in 
respect  of  receiving  this  nature  that  we  are  said  to  be  born 
again  sons  of  God. 

And  thus,  even  as  the  natural  light  of  reason  is  some- 
thing besides  the  acquired  virtues,  which  are  ordained  to 
this  natural  light,  so  also  the  light  of  grace  which  is  a  par- 
ticipation of  the  Divine  Nature  is  something  besides  the 
infused  virtues  which  are  derived  from  and  are  ordained  to 
this  light,  hence  the  Apostle  says  (Eph.  v.  8) :  For  you  were 
heretofore  darkness,  hut  now  light  in  the  Lord.  Walk  then  as 
children  of  the  light.  For  as  the  acquired  virtues  enable  a 
man  to  walk,  in  accordance  with  the  natural  light  of  reason, 
so  do  the  infused  virtues  enable  a  man  to  walk  as  befits  the 
light  of  grace. 


353  THE  GRACE  OF  GOD  Q.  no.  Art.  4 

Reply  Obj.  I.  Augustine  calls /a//A  tliat  workcth  by  cJiariiy 
grace,  since  the  act  of  faith  of  him  that  worketh  by  charity 
is  the  first  act  by  which  sanctifying  grace  is  manifested. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Good  is  placed  in  the  defmition  of  virtue 
with  reference  to  its  fitness  with  some  pre-existing  nature 
essential  or  participated.  Now  good  is  not  attributed 
to  grace  in  this  manner,  but  as  to  the  root  of  goodness  in 
man,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Grace  is  reduced  to  the  hrst  species  of 
quality;  and  yet  it  is  not  the  same  as  virtue,  but  is  a  cer- 
tain disposition  which  is  presupposed  to  the  infused  virtues, 
as  their  principle  and  root. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  grace  is  in  the  essence  of  the  soul  as  in  a 
subject,  or  in  one  of  the  powers  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  grace  is  not  in  the  essence  of 
the  soul,  as  in  a  subject,  but  in  one  of  the  powers.  For 
Augustine  says  {Hypognost.  iii.)  that  grace  is  related  to  the 
will  or  to  the  free  will  as  a  rider  to  his  horse.  Now  the  will 
or  the  free-will  is  a  power,  as  stated  above  (Part  I.,  Q. 
LXXXIIL,  A.  2).  Hence  grace  is  in  a  power  of  the  soul, 
as  in  a  subject. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Man's  merit  springs  from  grace  as  Augus- 
tine says  (De  Gratia  et  Lib.  Arbit.  iv.).  Now  merit  consists 
in  acts,  which  proceed  from  a  power.  Hence  it  seems  that 
grace  is  a  perfection  of  a  powxr  of  the  soul. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  if  the  essence  of  the  soul  is  the  proper 
subject  of  grace,  the  soul,  inasmuch  as  it  has  an  essence, 
must  be  capable  of  grace.  But  this  is  false;  since  it  would 
follow  that  every  soul  would  be  capable  of  grace.  Therefore 
the  essence  of  the  soul  is  not  the  proper  subject  of  grace. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  the  essence  of  the  soul  is  prior  to  its 
powers.  Now  what  is  prior  may  be  understood  without 
what  is  posterior.  Hence  it  follows  that  grace  may  be 
taken  to  be  in  the  soul,  although  we  suppose  no  part  or 

II.  3  23 


Q.  no.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  354 

power  of  the  soul — viz.,  neither  the  will,  nor  the  intellect, 
nor  anything  else;  which  is  impossible. 

On  the  contrary,  By  grace  we  are  born  again  sons  of  God. 
But  generation  terminates  at  the  essence  prior  to  the 
powers.  Therefore  grace  is  in  the  soul's  essence  prior  to 
being  in  the  powers. 

/  answer  that,  This  question  depends  on  the  preceding. 
For  if  grace  is  the  same  as  virtue,  it  must  necessarily  be  in 
the  powers  of  the  soul  as  in  a  subject;  since  the  soul's  powers 
are  the  proper  subject  of  virtue  as  stated  above  (Q.  LVL, 
A.  i).  But  if  grace  differs  from  virtue,  it  cannot  be  said 
that  a  power  of  the  soul  is  the  subject  of  grace,  since  every 
perfection  of  the  soul's  powers  has  the  nature  of  virtue, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  LV.,  A.  i;  Q.  LVL,  A.  i).  Hence  it 
remains  that  grace,  as  it  is  prior  to  virtue,  so  has  it  a  subject 
prior  to  the  powers  of  the  soul,  so  that  it  is  in  the  essence  of 
the  soul.  For  as  man  in  his  intellective  power  participates 
in  the  Divine  knowledge  through  the  virtue  of  faith,  and 
in  his  power  of  will  participates  in  the  Divine  love  through 
the  virtue  of  charity,  so  also  in  the  nature  of  the  soul  does 
he  participate  in  the  Divine  Nature,  after  the  manner  of  a 
likeness,  through  a  certain  regeneration  or  re-creation. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  from  the  essence  of  the  soul  flow  its 
powers,  which  are  the  principles  of  deeds,  so  likewise  the 
virtues,  whereby  the  powers  are  moved  to  act,  flow  into 
the  powers  of  the  soul  from  grace.  And  thus  grace  is  com- 
pared to  the  will  as  the  mover  to  the  moved,  which  is  the 
same  comparison  as  that  of  a  horseman  to  the  horse — but 
not  as  an  accident  to  a  subject. 

And  thereby  is  made  clear  the  Reply  to  the  second  objec- 
tion. For  grace  is  the  principle  of  meritorious  works 
through  the  medium  of  virtues,  as  the  essence  of  the  soul  is 
the  principle  of  vital  deeds  through  the  medium  of  the 
powers. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  soul  is  the  subject  of  grace,  as  being  in 
the  species  of  intellectual  or  rational  nature.  But  the  soul 
is  not  classed  in  a  species  by  any  of  its  powers,  since  the 
powers  are  natural  properties  of  the  soul  following  upon 


355  THE  GRACE  OF  GOD  o.  no.  Art.  4 

the  species.  Hence  the  soiil  differs  specifically  in  its  essence 
from  other  souls,  viz.,  of  dumb  animals  and  of  plants. 
Consequently  it  does  not  follow  that,  if  the  essence  of  the 
human  soul  is  the  subject  of  grace,  every  soul  may  be  the 
subject  of  grace;  since  it  belongs  to  the  essence  of  the  soul, 
inasmuch  as  it  is  of  such  a  species. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Since  the  powers  of  the  soul  are  natural 
properties  following  upon  the  species,  the  soul  cannot  be 
without  them.  Yet,  granted  that  it  was  without  them,  the 
soul  would  still  be  called  intellectual  or  rational  in  its  species, 
not  that  it  would  actually  have  these  powers,  but  on  account 
of  the  essence  of  such  a  species,  from  which  these  powers 
naturally  flow 


QUESTION  CXI. 

OF  THE  DIVISION  OF  GRACE. 

{In  Five  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  division  of  grace;  under  which 
head  there  are  five  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  grace  is 
fittingly  divided  into  gratuitous  grace  and  sanctifying 
grace  ?  (2)  Of  the  division  into  operating  and  co-operating 
grace.  (3)  Of  the  division  of  it  into  preventive  and  sub- 
sequent grace.  (4)  Of  the  division  of  gratuitous  grace. 
(5)  Of  the  comparison  between  sanctifying  and  gratuitous 
grace. 

First  Article. 

whether  grace  is  fittingly  divided  into  sanctifying 
grace  and  gratuitous  grace  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  grace  is  not  fittingly  divided 
into  sanctifying  grace  and  gratuitous  grace.  For  grace  is  a 
gift  of  God,  as  is  clear  from  what  has  been  already  stated 
(Q.  ex.,  A.  i).  But  man  is  not  therefore  pleasing  to  God 
because  something  is  given  him  by  God,  but  rather  on  the 
contrary;  since  something  is  freely  given  by  God,  because 
man  is  pleasing  to  Him.  Hence  there  is  no  sanctifying 
grace. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  whatever  is  not  given  on  account  of 
preceding  merits  is  given  gratis.  Now  even  natural  good 
is  given  to  man  without  preceding  merit,  since  nature  is 
presupposed  to  merit.  Therefore  nature  itself  is  given 
gratuitously  by  God.  But  nature  is  condivided  with  grace. 
Therefore  to  be  gratuitously  given  is  not  fittingly  set  down 

356 


357  THE  DIVISION  OF  GRACE     Q.  utArt.  i 

as  a  difference  of  grace,  since  it  is  found  outside  the  genus 
of  grace. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  members  of  a  division  arc  mutually 
opposed.  But  even  sanctifying  grace,  whereby  we  are 
justified,  is  given  to  us  gratuitously,  according  to  Rom. 
iii.  24:  Being  justified  freely  (gratis)  by  His  grace.  Hence 
sanctifying  grace  ought  not  to  be  divided  against  gratuitous 
grace. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  attributes  both  to  grace, 
viz.,  to  sanctify  and  to  be  gratuitously  given.  For  with 
regard  to  the  first  he  says  (Eph.  i.  6) :  He  hath  graced  tis  in 
His  beloved  Son.  And  with  regard  to  the  second  (Rom. 
ii.  6) :  And  if  by  grace,  it  is  not  now  by  works,  otherwise  grace 
is  no  more  grace.  Therefore  grace  can  be  distinguished  by 
its  having  one  only  or  both. 

/  answer  that.  As  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  xiii.  i),  those 
things  that  are  of  God  are  well  ordered  (Vulg., — those  that  are, 
are  ordained  by  God).  Now  the  order  of  things  consists  in 
this,  that  things  are  led  to  God  by  other  things,  as  Diony- 
sius  says  [Coel.  Hier.  iv.) .  And  hence  since  grace  is  ordained 
to  lead  men  to  God,  this  takes  place  in  a  certain  order,  so 
that  some  are  led  to  God  by  others. 

And  thus  there  is  a  twofold  grace; — one  whereby  man 
himself  is  united  to  God,  and  this  is  called  sanctifying  grace;\ 
— the  other  is  that  whereby  one  man  co-operates  with  another 
in  leading  him  to  God,  and  this  gift  is  called  gratuitous  *^ 
grace,  since  it  is  bestowed  on  a  man  beyond  the  capability 
of  nature,  and  beyond  the  merit  of  the  person.  But  whereas 
it  is  bestowed  on  a  man,  not  to  justify  him,  but  rather 
that  he  may  co-operate  in  the  justification  of  another, 
it  is  not  called  sanctifying  grace.  And  it  is  of  this  that 
the  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  xii.  7):  And  the  manifestation  of  the 
Spirit  is  given  to  every  man  unto  utility,  i.e.,  of  others. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Grace  is  said  to  make  pleasing,  not  effi- 
ciently, but  formally,  i.e.,  because  thereby  a  man  is  justified, 
and  is  made  worthy  to  be  called  pleasing  to  God,  according 
to  Col.  i.  21.  He  hath  made  us  worthy  to  be  made  partakers 
of  the  lot  of  the  saints  in  light. 


Q.  III.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  358 

Reply  Ob],  2.  Grace,  inasmuch  as  it  is  gratuitously  given, 
excludes  the  notion  of  debt.  Now  debt  may  be  taken  in 
two  ways: — first,  as  arising  from  merit;  and  this  regards  the 
person  whose  it  is  to  do  meritorious  works,  according  to 
Rom.  iv.  4:  Now  to  him  that  worketh,  the  reiiuard  is  not  reckoned 
according  to  grace,  hut  according  to  debt.  The  second  debt 
regards  the  condition  of  nature.  Thus  we  say  it  is  due  to 
a  man  to  have  reason,  and  whatever  else  belongs  to  human 
nature.  Yet  in  neither  way  is  debt  taken  to  mean  that  God 
is  under  an  obligation  to  His  creature,  but  rather  that  the 
creature  ought  to  be  subject  to  God,  that  the  Divine  ordina- 
tion may  be  fulfilled  in  it,  which  is  that  a  certain  nature 
should  have  certain  conditions  or  properties,  and  that  by 
doing  certain  works  it  should  attain  to  something  further. 
And  hence  natural  endowments  are  not  a  debt  in  the  first 
sense  but  in  the  second.  But  supernatural  gifts  are  due  in 
neither  sense.  Hence  they  especially  merit  the  name  of 
grace. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Sanctifying  grace  adds  to  the  notion  of 
gratuitous  grace  something  pertaining  to  the  nature  of 
grace,  since  it  makes  man  pleasing  to  God.  And  hence 
gratuitous  grace  which  does  not  do  this  keeps  the  common 
name,  as  happens  in  many  other  cases;  and  thus  the  two 
parts  of  the  division  are  opposed  as  sanctifying  and  non- 
sanctifying  grace. 

Second  Article. 

whether  grace  is  fittingly  divided  into  operating 
and  co-operating  grace  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article: — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  grace  is  not  fittingly  divided 
into  operating  and  co-operating  grace.  For  grace  is  an 
accident,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CX.,  A.  2).  Now  no  accident 
can  act  upon  its  subject.  Therefore  no  grace  can  be  called 
operating. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  if  grace  operates  anything  in  us  it 
assuredly  brings  about  justification.  But  not  only  grace 
works   this.     For   Augustine   says,   on   John   xiv.    12,   the 


359  THE  DIVISION  OF  (iRACE     Q.  iTr.ART.2 

works  that  I  do  he  also  shall  do,  says  [Scrni.  clxix.) :  lie  M'Jio 
created  thee  ivitJiout  thyself,  xcill  not  justify  tliee  u'lthont 
thyself.  Therefore  no  grace  ought  to  be  called  simply 
operating. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  to  co-operate  seems  to  pertain  to  the 
inferior  agent,  and  not  to  the  principal  agent.  But  grace 
works  in  us  more  than  free-will,  according  to  Rom.  ix.  16: 
It  is  not  of  him  that  willeth,  nor  of  him  that  runneth,  hit  of 
God  that  sheweth  mercy.  Therefore  no  grace  ought  to  be 
called  co-operating. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  division  ought  to  rest  on  opposition. 
But  to  operate  and  to  co-operate  are  not  opposed;  for  one 
and  the  same  thing  can  both  operate  and  co-operate. 
Therefore  grace  is  not  fittingly  divided  into  operating  and 
co-operating. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Gratia  et  Lib. 
Arbit.  xvii.) :  God  by  co-operating  with  us,  perfects  what  He 
began  by  operating  in  us,  since  He  who  perfects  by  co-operation 
with  such  as  are  willing,  begins  by  operating  that  they  may 
will.  But  the  operations  of  God  whereby  He  moves  us  to 
good  pertain  to  grace.  Therefore  grace  is  fittingly  divided 
into  operating  and  co-operating. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CX.,  A.  2)  grace  may 
be  taken  in  two  ways ;  firbt,  as  a  Divine  help,  whereby  God 
moves  us  to  will  and  to  act;  secondly,  as  a  habitual  gift 
divinely  bestowed  on  us. 

Now  in  both  these  ways  grace  is  fittingly  divided  into 
operating  and  co-operating.  For  the  operation  of  an  effect 
is  not  attributed  to  the  thing  moved  but  to  the  mover. 
Hence  in  that  effect  in  which  our  mind  is  moved  and  does 
not  move,  but  in  which  God  is  the  sole  mover,  the  operation 
is  attributed  to  God,  and  it  is  with  reference  to  this  that 
we  speak  of  operating  grace.  But  in  that  effect  in  which 
our  mind  both  moves  and  is  moved,  the  operation  is  not 
only  attributed  to  God,  but  also  to  the  soul;  and  it  is  with 
reference  to  this  that  we  speak  of  co-operating  grace.  Now 
there  is  a  double  act  in  us.  First,  there  is  the  interior  act 
of  the  will,  and  with  regard  to  this  act  the  will  is  a  thing 


Q.  III.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  360 

moved,  and  God  is  the  mover ;  and  especially  when  the  will, 
which  hitherto  willed  evil,  begins  to  will  good.  And  hence, 
inasmuch  as  God  moves  the  human  mind  to  this  act,  we 
speak  of  operating  grace.  But  there  is  another,  exterior 
act;  and  since  it  is  commanded  by  the  will,  as  was  shown 
above  (Q.  XVII.,  A.  9)  the  operation  of  this  act  is  attributed 
to  the  will.  And  because  God  assists  us  in  this  act,  both 
by  strengthening  our  will  interiorly  so  as  to  attain  to  the 
act,  and  by  granting  outwardly  the  capability  of  operating, 
it  is  with  respect  to  this  that  we  speak  of  co-operating  grace. 
Hence  after  the  aforesaid  words  Augustine  subjoins:  He 
operates  that  we  may  will;  and  when  we  will,  He  co-operates 
that  we  may  perfect.  And  thus  if  grace  is  taken  for  God's 
gratuitous  motion  whereby  He  moves  us  to  meritorious  good, 
it  is  fittingly  divided  into  operating  and  co-operating  grace. 

But  if  grace  is  taken  for  the  habitual  gift,  then  again 
there  is  a  double  effect  of  grace,  even  as  of  every  other 
form;  the  first  of  which  is  being,  and  the  second,  operation; 
thus  the  work  of  heat  is  to  make  its  subject  hot,  and  to 
give  heat  outwardly.  And  thus  habitual  grace,  inasmuch  as 
it  heals  and  justifies  the  soul,  or  makes  it  pleasing  to  God,  is 
called  operating  grace;  but  inasmuch  as  it  is  the  principle 
of  meritorious  works,  which  spring  from  the  free-will,  it  is 
called  co-operating  grace. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Inasmuch  as  grace  is  a  certain  accidental 
quality,  it  does  not  act  upon  the  soul  efficiently,  but  formally, 
as  whiteness  makes  a  surface  white. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  God  does  not  justify  us  without  ourselves, 
because  whilst  we  are  being  justified  we  consent  to  God's 
justification  [justitice)  by  a  movement  of  our  free  -  will. 
Nevertheless  this  movement  is  not  the  cause  of  grace, 
but  the  effect ;  hence  the  whole  operation  pertains  to  grace. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  One  thing  is  said  to  co-operate  with  another 
not  merely  when  it  is  a  secondary  agent  under  a  principal 
agent,  but  when  it  helps  to  the  end  intended.  Now  man 
is  helped  by  God  to  will  the'  good,  through  the  means  of 
operating  grace.  And  hence,  the  end  being  already  intended, 
grace  co-operates  with  us. 


36i  THE  DIVISION  OF  (xRACK     ().  iii.Ain.  3 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Operating  and  co-operating  grace  are  the 
same  grace;  but  are  distinguished  by  their  different  effects, 
as  is  plain  from  what  has  been  said. 


Third   Article. 

whether  grace  is  fittingly  divided  into  prevenient 
and  subsequent  grace  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  grace  is  not  fittingly  divided 
into  prevenient  and  subsequent.  For  grace  is  an  effect  of 
the  Divine  love.  But  God's  love  is  never  subsequent,  but 
always  prevenient,  according  to  i  John  iv.  10:  Not  as 
though  ive  had  loved  God,  but  because  He  hath  first  loved  us. 
Therefore  grace  ought  not  to  be  divided  into  prevenient  and 
subsequent. 

Ob].  2.  Further,  there  is  but  one  sanctifying  grace  in 
man,  since  it  is  sufficient,  according  to  2  Cor.  xii.  g:  My 
grace  is  sufficient  for  thee.  But  the  same  thing  cannot  be 
before  and  after.  Therefore  grace  is  not  fittingly  divided 
into  prevenient  and  subsequent. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  grace  is  known  by  its  effects.  Now 
there  are  an  infinite  number  of  effects, — one  preceding 
another.  Hence  if  with  regard  to  these,  grace  must  be 
divided  into  prevenient  and  subsequent,  it  would  seem 
that  there  are  infinite  species  of  grace.  Now  no  art  takes 
note  of  the  infinite  in  number.  Hence  grace  is  not  fittingly 
divided  into  prevenient  and  subsequent. 

On  the  contrary,  God's  grace  is  the  outcome  of  His  mercy. 
Now  both  are  said  in  Ps.  Iviii.  11 :  His  mercy  shall  prevent  me, 
and  again,  Ps.  xxii.  6:  Thy  mercy  will  follow  me.  Therefore 
grace  is  fittingly  divided  into  prevenient  and  subsequent. 

I  answer  that,  As  grace  is  divided  into  operating  and  co- 
operating, with  regard  to  its  diverse  effects,  so  also  is  it 
divided  into  prevenient  and  subsequent,  howsoever  we 
consider  grace.  Now  there  are  five  effects  of  grace  in  us: 
of  these,  the  first  is,  to  heal  the  soul;  the  second,  to  desire 
good;   the   third,   to   carry  into  effect  the  good  proposed; 


Q.  1 1 T.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  362 

the  fourth,  to  persevere  in  good;  the  fifth,  to  reach  glory. 
And  hence  grace,  inasmuch  as  it  causes  the  first  effect  in  us, 
is  called  prevenient  with  respect  to  the  second,  and  inasmuch 
as  it  causes  the  second,  it  is  called  subsequent  with  respect 
to  the  first  effect.  And  as  one  effect  is  posterior  to  this 
effect,  and  prior  to  that,  so  may  grace  be  called  prevenient 
and  subsequent  on  account  of  the  same  effect  viewed 
relatively  to  divers  others.  And  this  is  what  Augustine 
says  [De  Natura  et  Gratia  xxxi.) :  It  is  frevenient,  inasmuch 
as  it  heals,  and  subsequent,  inasmuch  as,  being  healed,  we  are 
strengthened;  it  is  prevenient,  inasmuch  as  we  are  called,  and 
subsequent,  inasmuch  as  we  are  glorified. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  God's  love  signifies  something  eternal; 
and  hence  can  never  be  called  anything  but  prevenient. 
But  grace  signifies  a  temporal  effect,  which  can  precede  and 
follow  another;  and  thus  grace  may  be  both  prevenient 
and  subsequent. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  division  into  prevenient  and  subsequent 
grace  does  not  divide  grace  in  its  essence,  but  only  in  its 
effects,  as  was  already  said  of  operating  and  co-operating 
grace.  For  subsequent  grace,  inasmuch  as  it  pertains  to 
glory,  is  not  numerically  distinct  from  prevenient  grace 
whereby  we  are  at  present  justified.  For  even  as  the 
charity  of  earth  is  not  voided  in  heaven,  so  must  the  same 
be  said  of  the  light  of  grace,  since  the  notion  of  neither 
implies  imperfection. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Although  the  effects  of  grace  may  be 
infinite  in  number,  even  as  human  acts  are  infinite,  neverthe- 
less all  are  reduced  to  some  of  a  determinate  species,  and 
moreover  all  coincide  in  this, — that  one  precedes  another. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  gratuitous  grace  is  rightly  divided  by  the 

APOSTLE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article: — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  gratuitous  grace  is  not  rightly 
divided  by  the  Apostle.     For  every  gift  vouchsafed  to  us  by 


363  THE  DIVISION  OF  GRACE     Q.  ui.Art.  4 

God,  may  be  called  a  gratuitous  grace.  Now  there  are  ai) 
inHnite  number  of  gifts  freely  bestowed  on  us  by  (iod  as 
regards  both  the  good  of  the  soul  and  the  good  of  the  body — 
and  yet  they  do  not  make  us  i)leasing  to  God.  Hence 
gratuitous  graces  cannot  be  contained  under  any  certain 
division. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  gratuitous  grace  is  distinguished  from 
sanctifying  grace.  But  faith  pertains  to  sanctifying  grace, 
since  we  are  justified  by  it,  according  to  Rom.  v.  i:  Being 
justified  therefore  by  faiih.  Hence  it  is  not  right  to  place 
faith  amongst  the  gratuitous  graces,  especially  since  the 
other  virtues  are  not  so  placed,  as  hope  and  charity. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  operation  of  healing,  and  speaking 
divers  tongues  are  miracles.  Again,  the  interpretation  of 
speeches  pertains  either  to  wisdom  or  to  knowledge,  accord- 
ing to  Dan.  i.  17:  And  to  these  children  God  gave  knoidedge 
and  understanding  in  every  book  and  imsdom.  Hence  it  is 
not  correct  to  divide  the  grace  of  healing  and  kinds  of  tongues 
against  the  working  of  miracles;  and  the  interpretation  of 
speeches  against  the  word  of  wisdom  and  knowledge. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  as  wisdom  and  knowledge  are  gifts  of  the 
Holy  Ghost,  so  also  are  understanding,  counsel,  piety,  forti- 
tude, and  fear,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXVIII.,  A.  4).  There- 
fore these  also  ought  to  be  placed  amongst  the  gratuitous 
gifts. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  xii.  8,  9,  10): 
To  one  indeed  by  the  Spirit  is  given  the  word  of  wisdom  ;  and 
to  another  the  word  of  knowledge,  according  to  the  same  Spirit, 
to  another,  the  working  of  miracles  ;  to  another,  prophecy  ;  to 
another,  the  discerning  of  spirits  ;  to  another  divers  kinds  of 
tongues  ;  to  another  interpretation  of  speeches. 

I  answer  that,  As  was  said  above  (A.  i),  gratuitous  grace 
is  ordained  to  this,  viz.,  that  a  man  may  help  another  to  be 
led  to  God.  Now  no  man  can  help  in  this  by  moving 
interiorly  (for  this  belongs  to  God  alone),  but  only  exteriorly 
by  teaching  or  persuading.  Hence  gratuitous  grace  em- 
braces whatever  a  man  needs  in  order  to  instruct  another 
in  Divine  things  which  arc  above  reason.     Now  for  this, 


Q.  III.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOCxICA  "  364 

three  things  are  required:  First,  a  man  must  possess  the 
fulness  of  knowledge  of  Divine  things,  so  as  to  be  capable 
of  teaching  others.  Secondly,  he  must  be  able  to  confirm  or 
prove  what  he  says,  otherwise  his  words  would  have  no 
weight.  Thirdly,  he  must  be  capable  of  fittingly  presenting 
to  his  hearers  what  he  knows. 

Now  as  regards  the  first,  three  things  are  necessary,  as 
may  be  seen  in  human  teaching.  For  whoever  would  teach 
another  in  any  science  must  first  be  certain  of  the  principles 
of  the  science,  and  with  regard  to  this  there  \s  faith,  which 
is  certitude  of  invisible  things,  the  principles  of  Catholic 
doctrine.  Secondly,  it  behoves  the  teacher  to  know  the 
principal  conclusions  of  the  science,  and  hence  we  have  the 
word  of  wisdom,  which  is  the  knowledge  of  Divine  things. 
Thirdly,  he  ought  to  abound  with  examples  and  a  knowledge 
of  effects,  whereby  at  times  he  needs  to  manifest  causes; 
and  thus  we  have  the  word  of  knowledge,  which  is  the  know- 
ledge of  human  things,  since  the  invisible  things  of  Him  .  .  . 
are  clearly  seen,  being  understood  by  the  things  that  are  made 
(Rom.  i.  20). 

Now  the  confirmation  of  such  things  as  are  within  reason 
rests  upon  arguments ;  but  the  confirmation  of  what  is  above 
reason  rests  on  what  is  proper  to  the  Divine  power,  and  this 
in  two  ways; — first  when  the  teacher  of  sacred  doctrine 
does  what  God  alone  can  do,  in  miraculous  deeds,  whether 
with  respect  to  bodily  health — and  thus  there  is  the  grace 
of  healing,  or  merely  for  the  purpose  of  manifesting  the 
Divine  power;  for  instance,  that  the  sun  should  stand  still 
or  darken,  or  that  the  sea  should  be  divided — and  thus 
there  is  the  working  of  miracles.  Secondly  when  he  can 
manifest  what  God  alone  can  know,  and  these  are  either 
future  contingents — and  thus  there  is  prophecy,  or  also  the 
secrets  of  hearts,  and  thus  there  is  the  discerning  of  spirits. 

But  the  capability  of  speaking  can  regard  either  the  idiom 
in  which  a  person  can  be  understood,  and  thus  there  is 
kinds  of  tongues  ;  or  it  can  regard  the  sense  of  what  is  said» 
and  thus  there  is  the  interpretation  of  speeches. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  not  all  the  benefits 


365  THE  DIVISION  OF  GRACE     Q.  hi.Art.  4 

divinely  conferred  upon  us  are  called  gratuitous  graces,  but 
only  those  that  surpass  the  power  of  nature — e.<f^.,  that  a 
fisherman  should  be  replete  with  the  word  of  wisdom  and  of 
knowledge  and  the  like ;  and  such  as  these  are  here  set  down 
as  gratuitous  graces. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Faith  is  enumerated  here  under  the  gratui- 
tous graces,  not  as  a  virtue  justifying  man  in  himself,  but 
as  implying  a  super-eminent  certitude  of  faith,  whereby  a 
man  is  fitted  for  instructing  others  concerning  such  things 
as  belong  to  the  faith.  With  regard  to  hope  and  charity, 
they  belong  to  the  appetitive  power,  according  as  man  is 
ordained  thereby  to  God. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  grace  of  healing  is  distinguished  from 
the  general  working  of  miracles  because  it  has  a  special 
reason  for  inducing  one  to  the  faith,  since  a  man  is  all 
the  more  ready  to  believe  when  he  has  received  the  gift  of 
bodily  health  through  the  virtue  of  faith.  So,  too,  to  speak 
with  divers  tongues  and  to  interpret  speeches  have  special 
efficacy  in  bestowing  faith.  Hence  they  are  set  down  as 
special  gratuitous  graces. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Wisdom  and  knowledge  are  not  numbered 
among  the  gratuitous  graces  in  the  same  way  as  they  are 
reckoned  among  the  gifts  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  i.e.,  inasmuch 
as  man's  mind  is  rendered  easily  movable  by  the  Holy 
Ghost  to  the  things  of  wisdom  and  knowledge ;  for  thus  they 
are  gifts  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXVIIL, 
AA.  I,  4).  But  they  are  numbered  amongst  the  gratuitous 
graces,  inasmuch  as  they  imply  such  a  fulness  of  knowledge 
and  wisdom  that  a  man  may  not  merely  think  aright  of 
Divine  things,  but  may  instruct  others  and  overpower 
adversaries.  Hence  it  is  significant  that  it  is  the  word  of 
wisdom  and  the  word  of  knowledge  that  are  placed  in  the 
gratuitous  graces,  since,  as  Augustine  says  {De  Trin.  xiv.). 
It  is  one  thing  merely  to  know  what  a  man  must  believe  in  order 
to  reach  everlasting  life,  and  another  thing  to  know  how  this 
may  benefit  the  godly  and  may  be  defended  against  the  un- 
godly. 


Q.  111.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  366 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  gratuitous  grace  is  nobler  than 
sanctifying  grace  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  gratuitous  grace  is  nobler  than 
sanctifying  grace.  For  the  people's  good  is  better  than  the 
individual  good,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  ii.).  Now 
sanctifying  grace  is  ordained  to  the  good  of  one  man  alone, 
whereas  gratuitous  grace  is  ordained  to  the  common  good 
of  the  whole  Church,  as  stated  above  (AA.  i,  4).  Hence 
gratuitous  grace  is  nobler  than  sanctifying  grace. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  it  is  a  greater  power  that  is  able  to  act 
upon  another,  than  that  which  is  confined  to  itself,  even  as 
greater  is  the  brightness  of  the  body  that  can  illuminate 
other  bodies,  than  of  that  which  can  only  shine  but  cannot 
illuminate;  and  hence  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  v.)  that 
justice  is  the  most  excellent  of  the  virtues,  since  by  it  a  man 
bears  himself  rightly  towards  others.  But  by  sanctifying 
grace  a  man  is  perfected  only  in  himself ;  whereas  by  gratui- 
tous grace  a  man  works  for  the  perfection  of  others.  Hence 
gratuitous  grace  is  nobler  than  sanctifying  grace. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  what  is  proper  to  the  best  is  nobler  than 
what  is  common  to  all ;  thus  to  reason,  which  is  proper  to  man 
is  nobler  than  to  feel,  which  is  common  to  all  animals. 
Now  sanctifying  grace  is  common  to  all  members  of  the 
Church,  but  gratuitous  grace  is  the  proper  gift  of  the  more 
exalted  members  of  the  Church.  Hence  gratuitous  grace  is 
nobler  than  sanctifying  grace. 

0)1  the  contrary.  The  Apostle  (i  Cor.  xii.  31),  having 
enumerated  the  gratuitous'  graces,  adds:  And  I  shew  unto 
you  yet  a  more  excellent  way  ;  and  as  the  sequel  proves  he  is 
speaking  of  charity,  which  pertains  to  sanctifying  grace. 
Hence  sanctifying  grace  is  more  noble  than  gratuitous 
grace. 

/  answer  that,  The  higher  the  good  to  which  a  virtue  is 
ordained,  the  more  excellent  is  the  virtue.  Now  the  end  is 
always    greater   than   the   means.     But   sanctifying   grace 


367  THE  DIVISION  OF  GRACE    o.  hi.Art.  5 

ordains  a  man  immediately  to  a  union  with  his  last  end, 
whereas  gratuitous  grace  ordains  a  man  to  what  is  pre- 
paratory to  the  end;  i.e.,  by  prophecy  and  miracles  and  so 
forth,  men  are  induced  to  unite  themselves  to  their  last 
end.  And  hence  sanctifying  grace  is  nobler  than  gratuitous 
grace. 

Reply  Obj.  I.  As  the  Philosopher  says  (Metaph.  xii.),  a 
multitude,  as  an  army,  has  a  double  good;  the  first  is  in  the 
multitude  itself,  viz.,  the  order  of  the  army;  the  second  is 
separate  from  the  multitude,  viz.,  the  good  of  the  leader: — 
and  this  is  the  better  good,  since  the  other  is  ordained  to  it. 
Now  gratuitous  grace  is  ordained  to  the  common  good  of 
the  Church,  w4iich  is  ecclesiastical  order,  whereas  sancti- 
fying grace  is  ordained  to  the  separate  common  good,  which 
is  God.     Hence  sanctifying  grace  is  the  nobler. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  If  gratuitous  grace  could  cause  a  man  to 
have  sanctifying  grace,  it  would  follow  that  gratuitous  grace 
was  the  nobler;  even  as  the  brightness  of  the  sun  that 
enlightens  is  more  excellent  than  that  of  an  object  that  is 
lit  up.  But  by  gratuitous  grace  a  man  cannot  cause  another 
to  have  union  with  God,  which  he  himself  has  by  sanctifying 
grace;  but  he  causes  certain  dispositions  towards  it.  Hence 
gratuitous  grace  needs  not  to  be  the  more  excellent,  even  as 
in  fire,  the  heat,  which  manifests  its  species  whereby  it  pro- 
duces heat  in  other  things,  is  not  more  noble  than  its  sub- 
stantial form. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Feeling  is  ordained  to  reason,  as  to  an  end; 
and  thus,  to  reason  is  nobler.  But  here  it  is  the  contrary; 
for  what  is  proper  is  ordained  to  what  is  common  as  10  an 
end.     Hence  there  is  no  comparison. 


QUESTION  CXII. 

OF  THE  CAUSE  OF  GRACE. 

[In  Five  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  cause  of  grace;  and  under  this 
head  there  are  five  points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether  God  alone 
is  the  efficient  cause  of  grace  ?  (2)  Whether  any  disposi- 
tion towards  grace  is  needed  on  the  part  of  the  recipient, 
by  an  act  of  free-will  ?  (3)  Whether  such  a  disposition  can 
make  grace  follow  of  necessity  ?  (4)  Whether  grace  is 
equal  in  all  ?  (5)  Whether  anyone  may  know  that  he  has 
grace  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  god  alone  is  the  cause  of  grace  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  God  alone  is  not  the  cause  of 
grace.  For  it  is  written  (John  i.  17) :  Grace  and  truth  came 
by  Jesus  Christ.  Now,  by  the  name  Jesus  Christ  is  under- 
stood not  merely  the  Divine  Nature  assuming,  but  the 
created  nature  assumed.  Therefore  a  creature  may  be  the 
cause  of  grace. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  there  is  this  difference  between  the 
sacraments  of  the  New  Law  and  those  of  the  Old,  that  the 
sacraments  of  the  New  Law  cause  grace,  whereas  the  sacra- 
ments of  the  Old  Law  merely  signify  it.  Now  the  sacra- 
ments of  the  New  Law  are  certain  visible  elements.  There- 
fore God  is  not  the  only  cause  of  grace. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  according  to  Dionysius  {Coel.  Hier.  iii., 
iv.,  vii.,  viii.),  Angels  cleanse,  enlighten,  and  perfect  both 
lesser  angels  and  men.     Now  the  rational  creature  is  cleansed, 

368 


369  THE  CAUSE  OF  GRACE       Q.  112.  Art.  i 

enlightened,  and  perfected  by  grace.  Therefore  God  is  not 
the  only  cause  of  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  Ixxxiii.  12) :  The  Lord 
will  give  grace  and  glory. 

I  ansiver  that,  Nothing  can  act  beyond  its  species,  since 
the  cause  must  always  be  more  powerful  than  its  effect. 
Now  the  gift  of  grace  surpasses  every  capability  of  created 
nature,  since  it  is  nothing  short  of  a  partaking  of  the  Divine 
Nature,  which  exceeds  every  other  nature.  And  thus  it  is 
impossible  that  any  creature  should  cause  grace.  For  it  is 
as  necessary  that  God  alone  should  deify,  bestowing  a  par- 
taking of  the  Divine  Nature  by  a  participated  likeness,  as 
it  is  impossible  that  anything  save  fire  should  enkindle. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Christ's  humanity  is  an  organ  of  His  God- 
head, as  Damascene  says  {De  Fide  Orthod.  iii).  Now  an 
instrument  does  not  bring  forth  the  action  of  the  principal 
agent  by  its  own  power,  but  in  virtue  of  the  principal  agent. 
Hence  Christ's  humanity  does  not  cause  grace  by  its  own 
power,  but  by  virtue  of  the  Divine  Nature  joined  to  it, 
whereby  the  actions  of  Christ's  humanity  are  saving  actions. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  As  in  the  person  of  Christ  the  humanity 
causes  our  salvation  by  grace,  the  Divine  power  being  the 
principal  agent,  so  likewise  in  the  sacraments  of  the  New 
Law,  which  are  derived  from  Christ,  grace  is  instrumentally 
caused  by  the  sacraments,  and  principally  by  the  power 
of  the  Holy  Ghost  working  in  the  sacraments,  according  to 
John  iii.  5 :  Unless  a  man  he  horn  again  of  water  and  the  Holy 
Ghost  he  cannot  enter  into  the  kingdom  of  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Angels  cleanse,  enlighten,  and  perfect  angels 
or  men,  by  instruction,  and  not  by  justifying  them  through 
grace.  Hence  Dionysius  says  [Coel.  Hier.  vii.)  that  this 
cleansing  and  enlightenment  and  perfecting  is  nothing  else 
than  the  assumption  of  Divine  knowledge. 


".3  24 


Q.  112.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  ''  370 

Second  Article, 
whether  any  preparation  and  disposition  for  grace 

IS    REQUIRED    ON    MAN'S    PART  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  no  preparation  or  disposition 
for  grace  is  required  on  man's  part,  since,  as  the  Apostle 
says  (Rom.  iv.  4),  To  him  that  worketh,  the  reward  is  not 
reckoned  according  to  grace,  but  according  to  debt.  Now  a 
man's  preparation  by  free-will  can  only  be  through  some 
operation.  Hence  it  would  do  away  with  the  notion  of 
grace. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  whoever  is  going  on  sinning,  is  not  pre- 
paring himself  to  have  grace.  But  to  some  who  are  going 
on  sinning  grace  is  given,  as  is  clear  in  the  case  of  Paul,  who 
received  grace  whilst  he  was  breathing  out  threatenings  and 
slaughter  against  the  disciples  of  the  Lord  (Acts  ix.  i).  Hence 
no  preparation  for  grace  is  required  on  man's  part. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  an  agent  of  infinite  power  needs  no 
disposition  in  matter,  since  it  does  not  even  require  matter, 
as  appears  in  creation,  to  which  grace  is  compared,  which  is 
called  a  new  creature  (Gal.  vi.  15).  But  only  God,  Who  has 
infinite  power,  causes  grace,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  Hence 
no  preparation  is  required  on  man's  part  to  obtain  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Amos  iv.  12) :  Be  prepared 
to  meet  thy  God,  0  Israel,  and  (i  Kings  vii.  3) :  Prepare  your 
hearts  unto  the  Lord. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXI.,  A.  2),  grace  is 
taken  in  two  ways: — First,  as  a  habitual  gift  of  God. 
Secondly,  as  a  help  from  God,  Who  moves  the  soul  to  good. 
Now  taking  grace  in  the  first  sense,  a  certain  preparation 
of  grace  is  required  for  it,  since  a  form  can  only  be  in  dis- 
posed matter.  But  if  we  speak  of  grace  as  it  signifies  a 
help  from  God  to  move  us  to  good,  no  preparation  is  re- 
quired on  man's  part,  that,  as  it  were,  anticipates  the  Divine 
help,  but  rather,  every  preparation  in  man  must  be  by  the 
help  of  God  moving  the  soul  to  good.  And  thus  even  the 
good  movement  of  the  free-will,  whereby  anyone  is  prepared 


371  THE  CAUSE  OF  GRACE       Q.  112.  Art.  2 

for  receiving  the  gift  of  grace  is  an  act  of  the  free-will 
moved  by  God.  And  thus  man  is  said  to  prepare  himself, 
according  to  Prov.  xvi.  i.  It  is  the  part  of  man  to  prepare 
the  soul ;  yet  it  is  principally  from  God,  Who  moves  the  free- 
will. Hence  it  is  said  that  man's  will  is  prepared  by  God, 
and  that  man's  steps  are  guided  by  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  I.  A  certain  preparation  of  man  for  grace  is' 
simultaneous  with  the  infusion  of  grace;  and  this  operation 
is  meritorious,  not  indeed  of  grace,  which  is  already  pos- 
sessed,— but  of  glory  which  is  not  yet  possessed.  But  there 
is  another  imperfect  preparation,  which  sometimes  precedes 
the  gift  of  sanctifying  grace,  and  yet  it  is  from  God's  motion. 
But  it  does  not  suffice  for  merit,  since  man  is  not  yet  justified 
by  grace,  and  merit  can  only  arise  from  grace,  as  will  be  seen 
farther  on  (Q.CXI  v.,  A.  2). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Since  a  man  cannot  prepare  himself  for 
grace  unless  God  prevent  and  move  him  to  good,  it  is  of 
no  account  whether  anyone  arrive  at  perfect  preparation 
instantaneously,  or  step  by  step.  For  it  is  written 
(Ecclus.  xi.  23) :  It  is-  easy  in  the  eyes  of  God  on  a  sudden  to 
make  the  poor  man  rich.  Now  it  sometimes  happens  that 
God  moves  a  man  to  good,  but  not  perfect  good,  and  this 
preparation  precedes  grace.  But  He  sometimes  moves  him 
suddenly  and  perfectly  to  good,  and  man  receives  grace 
suddenly,  according  to  John  vi.  45:  Everyone  that  hath 
heard  of  the  Father  and  hath  learned,  cometh  to  Me.  And 
thus  it  happened  to  Paul,  since,  suddenly  when  he  was  in 
the  midst  of  sin,  his  heart  was  perfectly  moved  by  God 
to  hear,  to  learn,  to  come;  and  hence  he  received  grace 
suddenly. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  An  agent  of  infinite  power  needs  no  matter 
or  disposition  of  matter,  brought  about  by  the  action  of 
something  else;  and  yet,  looking  to  the  condition  of  the 
thing  caused,  it  must  cause,  in  the  thing  caused,  both  the 
matter  and  the  due  disposition  for  the  form.  So  likewise, 
when  God  infuses  grace  into  a  soul,  no  preparation  is  re- 
quired which  He  Himself  does  not  bring  about. 


Q.  112.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  372 

Third  Article. 

whether    grace    is    necessarily    given    to    whoever 
prepares  himself  for  it,  or  to  whoever  does  what 

HE  CAN  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  grace  is  necessarily  given  to 
whoever  prepares  himself  for  grace,  or  to  whoever  does 
what  he  can,  because,  on  Rom.  v.  i.  Being  justified  .  .  .  by 
faith,  let  us  have  peace,  etc.,  the  gloss  says:  God  welcomes 
whoever  flies  to  Him,  otherwise  there  would  be  injustice  with 
Him.  But  it  is  impossible  for  injustice  to  be  with  God. 
Therefore  it  is  impossible  for  God  not  to  welcome  whoever 
flies  to  Him.     Hence  he  receives  grace  of  necessity. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Anselm  says  {De  Casu  Diaboli.  iii.)  that 
the  reason  why  God  does  not  bestow  grace  on  the  devil,  is 
that  he  did  not  wish,  nor  was  he  prepared,  to  receive  it. 
But  if  the  cause  be  removed,  the  effect  must  needs  be  re- 
moved also.  Therefore,  if  anyone  is  willing  to  receive  grace 
it  is  bestowed  on  them  of  necessity. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  good  is  diffusive  of  itself,  as  appears  from 
Dionysius  {Div.  Nom.  iv.).  Now  the  good  of  grace  is  better 
than  the  good  of  nature.  Hence,  since  natural  forms  neces- 
sarily come  to  disposed  matter,  much  more  does  it  seem 
that  grace  is  necessarily  bestowed  on  whoever  prepares 
himself  for  grace. 

On  the  contrary^  Man  is  compared  to  God  as  clay  to  the 
potter,  according  to  Jer.  xviii.  6:  As  clay  is  in  the  hand  of 
the  potter,  so  are  you  in  My  hand.  But  however  much  the 
clay  is  prepared,  it  does  not  necessarily  receive  its  shape  from 
the  potter.  Hence,  however  much  a  man  prepares  himself, 
he  does  not  necessarily  receive  grace  from  God. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  2),  man's  preparation 
for  grace  is  from  God,  as  Mover,  and  from  the  free-will,  as 
moved.  Hence  the  preparation  may  be  looked  at  in  two 
^ays: — First,  as  it  is  from  free-will,  and  thus  there  is  no 
necessity  that  it  should  obtain  grace,  since  the  gift  of  grace 
exceeds  every  preparation  of  human  power.     But  it  may  be 


373  THE  CAUSE  OF  GRACE        Q.  112.  Am.  3 

considered,  secondly,  as  it  is  from  God  the  Mover,  and  thus 
it  has  a  necessity — not  indeed  of  coercion,  but  of  infalli- 
bility— as  regards  what  it  is  ordained  to  by  God,  since  God's 
intention  cannot  fail,  according  to  the  saying  of  Augustine 
in  his  book  on  the  Predestination  of  the  Saints  (De  Dono 
Perscv.  xiv.)  that  by  God's  good  gifts  whoever  is  liberated,  is 
most  certainly  liberated.  Hence  if  God  intends,  while 
moving,  that  the  one  whose  heart  He  moves  should  attain 
to  grace,  he  will  infallibly  attain  to  it,  according  to 
John  vi.  45:  Every  one  that  hath  heard  of  the  Father  and  hath 
learned  cometh  to  Me. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  This  gloss  is  speaking  of  such  as  fly  to  God 
by  a  meritorious  act  of  their  free-will,  already  informed 
with  grace;  for  if  they  did  not  receive  grace,  it  would  be 
against  the  justice  which  He  Himself  established. — Or  if  it 
refers  to  the  movement  of  free-will  before  grace,  it  is  speak- 
ing in  the  sense  that  man's  flight  to  God  is  by  a  Divine 
motion,  which  ought  not,  in  justice,  to  fail. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  first  cause  of  the  defect  of  grace  is  on 
our  part ;  but  the  first  cause  of  the  bestowal  of  grace  is  on 
God's,  according  to  Osee  xiii.  9:  Destrtiction  is  thy  own,  0 
Israel ;  thy  help  is  only  in  Me. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Even  in  natural  things,  the  form  does  not 
necessarily  ensue  the  disposition  of  the  matter,  except  by 
the  power  of  the  agent  that  causes  the  disposition. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  grace  is  greater  in  one  than  in  another  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  grace  is  not  greater  in  one  than 
in  another.  For  grace  is  caused  in  us  by  the  Divine  love,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  CX.,  A.  i).  Now  it  is  written  (Wis.  vi.  8) : 
He  made  the  little  and  the  great  and  He  hath  equally  care  of  all. 
Therefore  all  obtain  grace  from  Him  equally. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  whatever  is  the  greatest  possible,  cannot 
be  more  or  less.  But  grace  is  the  greatest  possible,  since  it 
joins  us  with  our  last  end.      Therefore  there  is  no  greater 


Q.  112.  Art.  4       THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  374 

or  less  in  it.      Hence   it  is   not  greater  in   one   than   in 
another. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  grace  is  the  soul's  life,  as  stated  above 
(0.  ex.,  A.  I,  ad  2).  But  there  is  no  greater  or  less  in  life. 
Hence,  neither  is  there  in  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Eph.  iv.  7) :  But  to  every  one 
of  us  is  given  grace  according  to  the  measure  of  the  giving  of 
Christ.  Now  what  is  given  in  measure,  is  not  given  to  all 
equally.     Hence  all  have  not  an  equal  grace. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  LH.,  AA.  i,  2;  Q.  LVL, 
A  A.  I,  2),  habits  can  have  a  double  magnitude: — one,  as 
regards  the  end  or  object,  as  when  a  virtue  is  said  to  be 
more  noble  through  being  ordained  to  a  greater  good;  the 
other  on  the  part  of  the  subject,  which  more  or  less  partici- 
pates in  the  habit  inhering  to  it. 

Now  as  regards  the  first  magnitude,  sanctifying  grace 
cannot  be  greater  or  less,  since,  of  its  nature,  grace  joins 
man  to  the  Highest  Good,  which  is  God.  But  as  regards 
the  subject,  grace  can  receive  more  or  less,  inasmuch  as  one 
may  be  more  perfectly  enlightened  by  grace  than  another. 
And  a  certain  reason  for  this  is  on  the  part  of  him  who 
prepares  himself  for  grace;  since  he  who  is  better  prepared 
for  grace,  receives  more  grace.  Yet  it  is  not  here  that  we 
must  seek  the  first  cause  of  this  diversity,  since  man  pre- 
pares himself,  only  inasmuch  as  his  free-will  is  prepared  by 
God.  Hence  the  first  cause  of  this  diversity  is  to  be  sought 
on  the  part  of  God,  Who  dispenses  His  gifts  of  grace  vari- 
ously, in  order  that  the  beauty  and  perfection  of  the  Church 
may  result  from  these  various  degrees;  even  as  He  insti- 
tuted the  various  conditions  of  things,  that  the  universe 
might  be  perfect.  Hence  after  the  Apostle  had  said 
(Eph.  iv.  7) :  To  every  one  of  us  is  given  grace  according  to 
the  measure  of  the  giving  of  Christ,  having  enumerated  the 
various  graces,  he  adds  {verse  12) :  For  the  perfecting  of  the 
saints  .  .  .  for  the  edifying  of  the  body  of  Christ. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  Divine  care  may  be  looked  at  in  two 
ways: — First,  as  regards  the  Divine  act,  which  is  simple 
and  uniform;  and  thus  His  care  looks  equally  to  all,  since 


375  THE  CAUSE  OF  GRACE       Q.  112.  Art.  5 

by  one  simple  act  He  administers  great  things  and  little. 
But,  scco)idly,  it  may  be  considered  in  those  things  which 
come  to  creatm-es  by  the  Divine  care  ;  and  thus,  inequality  is 
found,  inasmuch  as  God  by  His  care  provides  greater  gifts 
for  some,  and  lesser  gifts  for  others. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  This  objection  is  based  on  the  first  kind  of 
magnitude  of  grace;  since  grace  cannot  be  greater  by  ordain- 
ing to  a  greater  good,  but  inasmuch  as  it  more  or  less  ordains 
to  a  greater  or  less  participation  of  the  same  good.  For 
there  may  be  diversity  of  intensity  and  remissness,  both  in 
grace  and  in  final  glory  as  regards  the  subjects'  participation. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Natural  life  pertains  to  man's  substance, 
and  hence  cannot  be  more  or  less;  but  man  partakes  of  the 
life  of  grace  accidentally,  and  hence  man  may  possess  it 
more  or  less. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  man  can  know  that  he  has  grace  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man  can  know  that  he  has 
grace.  For  grace  by  its  physical  reality  is  in  the  soul. 
Now  the  soul  has  most  certain  knowledge  of  those  things 
that  are  in  it  by  their  physical  reality,  as  appears  from 
Augustine  [Gen.  ad  lit.  xii.).  Hence  grace  may  be  known 
most  certainly  by  one  who  has  grace. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  as  knowledge  is  a  gift  of  God,  so  is  grace. 
But  whoever  receives  knowledge  from  God,  knows  that  he 
has  knowledge,  according  to  Wis.  vii.  17:  The  Lord  hath 
given  me  the  true  knowledge  of  the  things  that  are.  Hence, 
with  equal  reason,  whoever  receives  grace  from  God,  knows 
that  he  has  grace. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  light  is  more  knowable  than  darkness, 
since,  according  to  the  Apostle  (Eph.  v.  13),  all  that  is  jnade 
manifest  is  light.  Now  sin,  which  is  spiritual  darkness, 
may  be  known  with  certainty  by  one  that  is  in  sin.  Much 
more,  therefore,  may  grace,  which  is  spiritual  light,  be  known. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  the  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  ii.  12) :  Now  we 
have  received  not  the  Spirit  of  this  world,  hut  the  Spirit  that  is 


Q  112.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  376 

of  God  ;  that  wc  may  know  the  things  that  arc  given  us  from 
God.  Now  grace  is  God's  first  gift.  Hence,  the  man  who 
receives  grace  by  the  Holy  Spirit,  by  the  same  Holy  Spirit 
knows  the  grace  given  to  him. 

Ohj.  5.  Further,  it  was  said  by  the  Lord  to  Abraham 
(Gen.  xxii.  12):  Now  I  know  that  thou  fearcst  God,  i.e.,  / 
have  made  thee  know.  Now  He  is  speaking  there  of  chaste 
fear,  which  is  not  apart  from  grace.  Hence  a  man  may 
know  that  he  has  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Eccles.  ix.  i) :  Man  knoweth 
not  whether  he  he  worthy  of  love  or  hatred.  Now  sanctifying 
grace  maketh  a  man  worthy  of  God's  love.  Therefore  no 
one  can  know  whether  he  has  sanctifying  grace. 

/  answer  that,  There  are  three  ways  of  knowing  a  thing: — 
First,  by  revelation,  and  thus  anyone  may  know  that  he 
has  grace,  for  God  by  a  special  privilege  reveals  this  at  times 
to  some,  in  order  that  the  joy  of  safety  may  begin  in  them 
even  in  this  life,  and  that  they  may  carry  on  toilsome  works 
with  greater  trust  and  greater  energy,  and  may  bear  the 
evils  of  this  present  life,  as  when  it  was  said  to  Paul 
(2  Cor.  xii.  9) :  My  grace  is  sufficient  for  thee. 

Secondly,  a  man  may,  of  himself,  know  something,  and 
with  certainty;  and  in  this  way  no  one  can  know  that  he 
has  grace.  For  certitude  about  a  thing  can  only  be  had 
when  we  may  judge  of  it  by  its  proper  principle.  Thus  it 
is  by  undemonstrable  universal  principles  that  certitude  is 
obtained  concerning  demonstrative  conclusions.  Now  no 
one  can  know  he  has  the  knowledge  of  a  conclusion  if  he 
does  not  know  its  principle.  But  the  principle  of  grace 
and  its  object  is  God,  Who  by  reason  of  His  very  excellence 
is  unknown  to  us,  according  to  Job  xxxvi.  26.  Behold  God 
is  great,  exceeding  our  knowledge.  And  hence  His  presence 
in  us  and  His  absence  cannot  be  known  with  certainty, 
according  to  Job  ix.  11:  //  He  come  to  me,  I  shall  not  see 
Him  ;  if  He  depart  I  shall  not  understand.  And  hence  man 
cannot  judge  with  certainty  that  he  has  grace,  according 
to  I  Cor.  iv.  3,  4:  But  neither  do  I  judge  my  own  self .  .  .  but 
He  that  judgeth  me  is  the  Lord. 


377  THE  CAUSE  OF  GRACE        Q.  112.  Art.  5 

Thirdly,  things  arc  known  conjccturally  by  signs;  and 
thus  anyone  may  know  he  has  grace,  when  he  is  conscious 
of  delighting  in  God,  and  of  despising  worldly  things,  and 
inasmuch  as  a  man  is  not  conscious  of  any  mortal  sin.  And 
thus  it  is  written  (Apoc.  ii.  17) :  To  him  that  overcometh  I  will 
give  the  hidden  manna  .  .  .  which  no  man  knoweth,  hut  he  that 
receiveth  it,  because  whoever  receives  it  knows,  by  ex- 
periencing a  certain  sweetness,  which  he  who  does  not 
receive  it,  does  not  experience.  Yet  this  knowledge  is 
imperfect;  hence  the  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  iv.  4):  /  am  not 
conscious  to  myself  of  anything,  yet  am  I  not  hereby  justified, 
since,  according  to  Ps.  xviii.  13 :  Who  can  understand  sins  P 
From  my  secret  ones  cleanse  nie,  0  Lord,  and  from  those  of 
others  spare  Thy  servant. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Those  things  which  are  in  the  soul  by  their 
physical  reality,  are  known  through  experimental  know- 
ledge; in  so  far  as  through  acts  man  has  experience  of 
their  inward  principles:  thus  when  we  wish,  we  perceive  that 
we  have  a  will;  and  when  we  exercise  the  functions  of  life, 
we  observe  that  there  is  life  in  us. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  It  is  an  essential  condition  of  knowledge 
that  a  man  should  have  certitude  of  the  objects  of  know- 
ledge; and  again,  it  is  an  essential  condition  of  faith  that  a 
man  should  be  certain  of  the  things  of  faith,  and  this, 
because  certitude  belongs  to  the  perfection  of  the  intellect, 
wherein  these  gifts  exist.  Hence,  whoever  has  knowledge 
or  faith  is  certain  that  he  has  them.  But  it  is  otherwise 
with  grace  and  charity  and  suchlike,  which  perfect  the 
appetitive  faculty. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Sin  has  for  its  principal  object  commutable 
good,  which  is  known  to  us.  But  the  object  or  end  of  grace 
is  unknown  to  us  on  account  of  the  greatness  of  its  light, 
according  to  i  Tim.  vi.  16:  Who  .  .  .  inhahiteth  light  inac- 
cessihle. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  The  Apostle  is  here  speaking  of  the  gifts 
of  glory,  which  have  been  given  to  us  in  hope,  and  these 
we  know  most  certainly  by  faith,  although  we  do  not  know 
for  certain  that  we  have  grace  to  enable  us  to  merit  them. — 


Q.  112.  Art.  5      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  378 

Or  it  may  be  said  that  he  is  speaking  of  the  privileged 
knowledge,  which  comes  of  revelation.  Hence  he  adds 
(verse  10) :  But  to  us  God  hath  revealed  them  by  His  Spirit. 

Reply  Ohj.  5.  What  was  said  to  Abraham  may  refer 
to  experimental  knowledge  which  springs  from  deeds  of 
which  we  are  cognizant.  For  in  the  deed  that  Abraham 
had  just  wrought,  he  could  know  experimentally  that  he  had 
the  fear  of  God. — Or  it  may  refer  to  a  revelation. 


QUESTION  CXIII. 

Ov   THE  EFFECTS  OF  GRACE. 

{1)1  Ten  Articles.) 

We  have  now  to  consider  the  effect  of  grace;  (i)  the  justi- 
fication of  the  ungodly,  which  is  the  effect  of  operating 
grace;  and  (2)  merit,  which  is  the  effect  of  co-operating 
grace.  Under  the  first  head  there  are  ten  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  What  is  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  ?  (2)  Whether 
grace  is  required  for  it  ?  (3)  Whether  any  movement  of  the 
free-will  is  required  ?  (4)  Whether  a  movement  of  faith  is 
required  ?  (5)  Whether  a  movement  of  the  free-will 
against  sin  is  required  ?  (6)  Whether  the  remission  of  sins 
is  to  be  reckoned  with  tlie  foregoing  ?  (7)  Whether  the 
justification  of  the  ungodly  is  a  work  of  time  or  is  sudden  ? 
(8)  Of  the  natural  order  of  the  things  concurring  to  justifi- 
cation. (9)  Whether  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  is 
God's  greatest  work  ?  (10)  Whether  the  justification  of 
the  ungodly  is  miraculous  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  the 

remission  of  sins  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  justification  of  the  ungodly 
is  not  the  remission  of  sins.  For  sin  is  opposed  not  only 
to  justice,  but  to  all  the  other  virtues,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  LXXL,  A.  i).  Now  justification  signifies  a  certain 
movement  towards  justice.  Therefore  not  even  remission 
of  sin  is  justification,  since  movement  is  from  one  contrary 
to  the  other. 

379 


Q.  113.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  380 

Obj.  2.  Further,  everything  ought  to  be  named  from  what 
is  predominant  in  it,  according  to  De  Aninia  ii.  Now  the 
remission  of  sins  is  brought  about  chiefly  by  faith,  according 
to  Acts  XV.  9:  Purifying  their  hearts  by  faith  ;  and  by  charity, 
according  to  Pro  v.  x.  12 :  Charity  cover  eth  all  sins.  Therefore 
the  remission  of  sins  ought  to  be  named  after  faith  or 
charity  rather  than  justice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  remission  of  sins  seems  to  be  the 
same  as  being  called,  for  whoever  is  called  is  afar  off,  and 
we  are  afar  off  from  God  by  sin.  But  one  is  called  before 
being  justified  according  to  Rom.  viii.  30:  And  whom  He 
called,  them  He  also  justified.  Therefore  justification  is  not 
the  remission  of  sins. 

On  the  contrary,  On  Rom.  viii.  30,  Whom  He  called,  them 
He  also  justified,  the  gloss  says,  i.e.,  by  the  remission  of  sins. 
Therefore  the  remission  of  sins  is  justification. 

/  answer  that,  Justification  taken  passively  implies  a 
movement  towards  justice,  as  heating  implies  a  movement 
towards  heat.  But  since  justice,  by  its  nature,  implies  a 
certain  rectitude  of  order,  it  may  be  taken  in  two  ways: — 
First,  inasmuch  as  it  implies  a  right  order  in  man's  act,  and 
thus  justice  is  placed  amongst  the  virtues, — either  as  par- 
ticular justice,  which  directs  a  man's  acts  by  regulating 
them  in  relation  to  his  fellow-man, — or  as  legal  justice, 
which  directs  a  man's  acts  by  regulating  them  in  their 
relation  to  the  common  good  of  society,  as  appears  from 
Ethic.  V. 

Secondly,  justice  is  so-called  inasmuch  as  it  implies  a  cer- 
tain rectitude  of  order  in  the  interior  disposition  of  a  man, 
in  so  far  as  what  is  highest  in  man  is  subject  to  God,  and  the 
inferior  powers  of  the  soul  are  subject  to  the  superior,  i.e., 
to  the  reason;  and  this  disposition  the  Philosopher  calls 
justice  metaphorically  speaking  {Ethic,  v.).  Now  this  justice 
may  be  in  man  in  two  ways: — First,  by  simple  generation, 
which  is  from  privation  to  form;  and  thus  justification  may 
belong  even  to  such  as  are  not  in  sin,  when  they  receive 
this  justice  from  God,  as  Adam  is  said  to  have  received 
original   justice.     Secondly,    this    justice   may  be   brought 


38i  THE  EFFECTS  OF  GRACE     Q.  113.  Art.  i 

about  in  man  by  a  movement  from  one  contrary  to  the 
other,  and  thus  justification  implies  a  transmutation  from 
the  state  of  injustice  to  the  aforesaid  state  of  justice.  And 
it  is  thus  we  are  now  speaking  of  the  justification  of  the 
ungodly,  according  to  the  Apostle  (Rom.  iv.  5) :  But  to  him 
that  worketh  not,  yet  helieveth  in  Him  that  justifieth  the  ungodly, 
etc.  And  because  movement  is  named  after  its  term 
ivhereto  rather  than  from  its  term  whence,  the  transmutation 
whereby  anyone  is  changed  by  the  remission  of  sins  from 
the  state  of  ungodliness  to  the  state  of  justice,  borrows  its 
name  from  its  term  whereto,  and  is  called  justification  of  the 
ungodly. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Every  sin,  inasmuch  as  it  implies  the  dis- 
order of  a  mind  not  subject  to  God,  may  be  called  injustice, 
as  being  contrary  to  the  aforesaid  justice,  according  to 
I  John  iii.  4:  Whosoever  committeth  sin,  committeth  also 
iniquity  ;  and  sin  is  iniquity.  And  thus  the  removal  of  any 
sin  is  called  the  justification  of  the  ungodly. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Faith  and  charity  imply  a  special  directing 
of  the  human  mind  to  God  by  the  intellect  and  will ;  whereas 
justice  implies  a  general  rectitude  of  order.  Hence  this 
transmutation  is  named  after  justice  rather  than  after 
charity  or  faith. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Being  called  refers  to  God's  help  moving 
and  exciting  our  mind  to  give  up  sin,  and  this  motion  of  God 
is  not  the  remission  of  sins,  but  its  cause. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  infusion  of  grace  is  required  for  the 
remission  of  guilt,  i.e.,  for  the  justification  of 
the    ungodly  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article: — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  for  the  remission  of  guilt,  which 
is  the  justification  of  the  migodly,  no  infusion  of  grace  is 
required.  For  anyone  may  be  moved  from  one  contrary 
without  being  led  to  the  other,  if  the  contraries  are  not 
immediate.     Now  the  state  of  guilt  and  the  state  of  grace 


Q.  113.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  382 

are  not  immediate  contraries;  for  there  is  the  middle  state 
of  innocence  wherein  a  man  has  neither  grace  nor  guilt. 
Hence  a  man  may  be  pardoned  his  guilt  without  his  being 
brought  to  a  state  of  grace. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  remission  of  guilt  consists  in  the 
Divine  imputation,  according  to  Ps.  xxxi.  2:  Blessed  is  the 
man  to  whom  the  Lord  hath  not  imputed  sin.  Now  the 
infusion  of  grace  puts  something  into  our  soul,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  CX.,  A.  i).  Hence  the  infusion  of  grace  is  not 
required  for  the  remission  of  guilt. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  no  one  can  be  subject  to  two  contraries 
at  once.  Now  some  sins  are  contraries,  as  wastefulness  and 
miserliness.  Hence  whoever  is  subject  to  the  sin  of  waste- 
fulness is  not  simultaneously  subject  to  the  sin  of  miserli- 
ness, yet  it  may  happen  that  he  has  been  subject  to  it 
hitherto.  Hence  by  sinning  with  the  vice  of  wastefulness 
he  is  freed  from  the  sin  of  miserliness.  And  thus  a  sin  is 
remitted  without  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Rom.  iii.  24) :  Justified  freely 
by  His  grace, 

I  answer  that,  By  sinning  a  man  offends  God,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  LXXI.,  A.  5).  Now  an  offence  is  remitted  to 
anyone,  only  when  the  soul  of  the  offender  is  at  peace  with 
the  offend^'^  Hence  sin  is  remitted  to  us,  when  God  is  at 
peace  with  us,  and  this  peace  consists  in  the  love  whereby 
God  loves  us.  Now  God's  love,  considered  on  the  part  of 
the  Divine  act,  is  eternal  and  unchangeable;  whereas,  as 
regards  the  effect  it  imprints  on  us,  it  is  sometimes  inter- 
rupted, inasmuch  as  we  sometimes  fall  short  of  it  and  once 
more  require  it.  Now  the  effect  of  the  Divine  love  in  us, 
which  is  taken  away  by  sin,  is  grace,  whereby  a  man  is 
made  worthy  of  eternal  life,  from  which  sin  shuts  him  out. 
Hence  we  could  not  conceive  the  remission  of  guilt,  without 
the  infusion  of  grace. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  More  is  required  for  an  offender  to  pardon 
an  offence,  than  for  one  who  has  committed  no  offence, 
not  to  be  hated.  For  it  may  happen  amongst  men  that 
one  man  neither  hates  nor  loves  another.     But  if  the  other 


383  THE  EFFFXTS  OF  GRACE     Q.  113.  Art.  2 

offends  him,  then  the  forgiveness  of  the  offence  can  only 
spring  from  a  special  good-will.  Now  God's  good-will  is 
said  to  be  restored  to  man  by  the  gift  of  grace;  and  hence 
although  a  man  before  sinning  may  be  without  grace  and 
without  guilt,  yet  that  he  is  without  guilt  after  sinning  can 
only  be  because  he  has  grace. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  God's  love  consists  not  merely  in  the 
act  of  the  Divine  will  but  also  implies  a  certain  effect  of 
grace,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CX.,  A.  i),  so  likewise,  when  God 
does  not  impute  sin  to  a  man,  there  is  implied  a  certain 
effect  in  him  to  whom  the  sin  is  not  imputed;  for  it  proceeds 
from  the  Divine  love,  that  sin  is  not  imputed  to  a  man  by 
God. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  Augustine  says  (De  Nup.  et  Concup.  i.), 
if  to  leave  off  sinning  was  the  same  as  to  have  no  sin,  it 
would  be  enough  if  Scripture  warned  us  thus :  '  My  son,  hast 
thou  sumed  ?  do  so  no  more  ?''  Now  this  is  not  enough,  but 
it  is  added:  '  But  for  thy  former  sins  also  pray  that  they  may 
be  forgiven  thee.'  For  the  act  of  sin  passes,  but  the  guilt 
remains,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXXVIL,  A.  6).  Hence  when 
anyone  passes  from  the  sin  of  one  vice  to  the  sin  of  a  con- 
trary vice,  he  ceases  to  have  the  act  of  the  former  sin,  but 
he  does  not  cease  to  have  the  guilt,  hence  he  may  have  the 
guilt  of  both  sins  at  once.  For  sins  are  not  contrary  to 
each  other  on  the  part  of  their  turning  from  God,  wherein 
sin  has  its  guilt. 

Third   Article. 

whether   for  the   justification   of  the   ungodly    is 
required  a  movement  of  the  free-will  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  no  movement  of  the  free-will 
is  required  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly.  For  we 
see  that  by  the  sacrament  of  Baptism,  infants  and  some- 
times adults  are  justified  without  a  movement  of  their  free- 
will: hence  Augustine  says  {Confess,  iv.)  that  when  one  of 
his  friends  was  taken  with  a  fever,  he  lay  for  a  long  time 
senseless  and  in  a  deadly  sweat,  and  when  he  i(>as  despaired 


Q  113.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  384 

0/,  he  was  baptized  without  his  knowing,  and  was  regenerated; 
which  is  effected  by  sanctifying  grace.  Now  God  does  not 
confine  His  power  to  the  sacraments.  Hence  He  can 
justify  a  man  without  the  sacraments,  and  without  any 
movement  of  the  free-will. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  a  man  has  not  the  use  of  reason  when 
asleep,  and  without  it  there  can  be  no  movement  of  the  free- 
will. But  Solomon  received  from  God  the  gift  of  wisdom 
when  asleep,  as  related  in  3  Kings  iii.  and  2  Paral.  i.  Hence 
with  equal  reason  the  gift  of  sanctifying  grace  is  sometimes 
bestowed  by  God  on  man  without  the  movement  of  his 
free-will. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  grace  is  preserved  by  the  same  cause 
as  brings  it  into  being,  for  Augustine  says  [Gen.  ad  lit.  xii.) 
that  so  ought  man  to  turn  to  God  as  he  is  ever  made  just  by  Him. 
Now  grace  is  preserved  in  man  without  a  movement  of  his 
free-will.  Hence  it  can  be  infused  in  the  beginning  without  a 
movement  of  the  free-will. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (John  vi.  45) :  Every  one 
that  hath  heard  of  the  Father,  and  hath  learned,  cometh  to  Me. 
Now  to  learn  cannot  be  without  a  movement  of  the  free-will, 
since  the  learner  assents  to  the  teacher.  Hence  no  one 
comes  to  the  Father  by  justifying  grace  without  a  movement 
of  the  free-will. 

/  answer  that,  The  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  brought 
about  by  God  moving  man  to  justice.  For  He  it  is  that 
justifieth  the  ungodly  according  to  Rom.  iv.  5.  Now  God 
moves  everything  in  its  own  manner,  just  as  we  see  that  in 
natural  things,  what  is  heavy  and  what  is  light  are  moved 
differently,  on  account  of  their  diverse  natures.  Hence  He 
moves  man  to  justice  according  to  the  condition  of  his 
human  nature.  But  it  is  man's  proper  nature  to  have  free- 
will. Hence  in  him  who  has  the  use  of  reason,  God's 
motion  to  justice  does  not  take  place  without  a  movement  of 
the  free-will;  but  He  so  infuses  the  gift  of  justifying  grace 
that  at  the  same  time  He  moves  the  free-will  to  accept  the 
gift  of  grace,  in  such  as  are  capable  of  being  moved  thus. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Infants  are  not  capable  of  the  movement  of 


385  THE  EFFECTS  OF  GRACE    Q.  1 13.  Art  j 

their  free-will;  hence  it  is  by  the  mere  infusion  of  their  souls 
that  God  moves  them  to  justice.  Now  this  cannot  be  brought 
about  without  a  sacrament;  because  as  original  sin,  from 
which  they  are  justified,  does  not  come  to  them  from  their 
own  will,  but  by  carnal  generation,  so  also  is  grace  given 
them  by  Christ  through  spiritual  regeneration.  And  the 
same  reason  holds  good  with  madmen  and  idiots,  that  have 
never  had  the  use  of  their  free-will.  But  in  the  case  of  one 
who  has  had  the  use  of  his  free-will  and  afterwards  has  lost  it 
either  through  sickness  or  sleep,  he  does  not  obtain  justi- 
fying grace  by  the  exterior  rite  of  Baptism,  or  of  any  other 
sacrament,  unless  he  intended  to  make  use  of  this  sacrament, 
and  this  can  only  be  by  the  use  of  his  free-will.  And  it 
was  in  this  way  that  he  of  wliom  Augustine  speaks  was 
regenerated,  because  both  previously  and  afterwards  he 
assented  to  the  Baptism. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Solomon  neither  merited  nor  received 
wisdom  whilst  asleep;  but  it  was  declared  to  him  in  his 
sleep  that  on  account  of  his  previous  desire  wisdom  would 
be  infused  into  him  by  God.  Hence  it  is  said  in  his 
person  (Wis.  vii.  7) :  /  wished,  and  understanding  was  given 
unto  me. 

Or  it  may  be  said  that  his  sleep  was  not  natural,  but 
was  the  sleep  of  prophecy,  according  to  Num.  xii.  6:  // 
there  be  among  you  a  prophet  of  the  Lord,  I  will  appear  to 
him  in  a  vision,  or  I  will  speak  to  him  in  a  dream.  In  such 
cases  the  use  of  free-will  remains. 

And  yet  it  must  be  observed  that  the  comparison  between 
the  gift  of  wisdom  and  the  gift  of  justifying  grace  does  not 
hold.  For  the  gift  of  justifying  grace  especially  ordains 
a  man  to  good,  which  is  the  object  of  the  will;  and  hence  a 
man  is  moved  to  it  by  a  movement  of  the  will  which  is  a 
movement  of  free-will.  But  wisdom  perfects  the  intellect 
which  precedes  the  will;  hence  without  any  complete  mo\'e- 
ment  of  the  free-will,  the  intellect  can  be  enlightened  with 
the  gift  of  wisdom,  even  as  we  see  that  things  are  re\'ealed 
to  men  in  sleep,  according  to  Job  xxxiii.  15,  16:  ]Vhe)i  deep 
sleep  falleth  upon  men  and  they  are  sleepi)ig  in  their  beds, 

"•  3  25 


Q.  113.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  386 

•  then  Ho  opencth   the  cars  of  men,  and  teachmg,  instructeth 
them  in  what  they  are  to  learn. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  the  infusion  of  justifying  grace  there  is 
a  certain  transmutation  of  the  human  soul,  and  hence  a 
proper  movement  of  the  human  soul  is  required  in  order 
that  the  soul  may  be  moved  in  its  own  manner.  But  the 
conservation  of  grace  is  without  transmutation :  no  move- 
ment on  the  part  of  the  soul  is  required  but  only  a  con- 
tinuation of  the  Divine  influx. 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  a  movement  of  faith  is  required  for  the 
justification  of  the  ungodly  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article: — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  no  movement  of  faith  is  required 
for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly.  For  as  a  man  is  justi- 
fied by  faith,  so  also  by  other  things,  viz.,  by  fear,  of  which 
it  is  written  (Ecclus.  i.  27):  The  fear  of  the  Lord  driveth  out 
sin,  for  he  that  is  without  fear  cannot  be  justified;  and  again  by 
charity,  according  to  Luke  vii.  47 :  Many  sins  are  forgiven 
her  because  she  hath  loved  much ;  and  again  by  humility, 
according  to  James  iv.  6:  God  resisteth  the  proud  and  giveth 
grace  to  the  humble:  and  again  by  mercy,  according  to  Pro  v. 
XV.  27 :  By  mercy  and  faith  sins  are  purged  away.  Hence 
the  movement  of  faith  is  no  more  required  for  the  justifica- 
tion of  the  ungodly,  than  the  movements  of  the  aforesaid 
virtues. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  act  of  faith  is  required  for  justification 
only  inasmuch  as  a  man  knows  God  by  faith.  But  a  man 
may  know  God  in  other  ways,  viz.,  by  natural  knowledge, 
and  by  the  gift  of  wisdom.  Hence  no  act  of  faith  is  required 
for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  there  are  several  articles  of  faith.  There- 
fore if  the  act  of  faith  is  required  for  the  justification  of  the 
ungodly,  it  would  seem  that  a  man  ought  to  think  on  every 
article  of  faith  when  he  is  first  justified.  But  this  seems 
inconvenient,  since  such  thought  would  require  a  long  delay 


387  THE  EFFECTS  OF  GRACE    0.113.  Art  4 

of  time.  Hence  it  seems  that  an  act  of  faith  is  not  required 
for  the  justilication  of  the  migodly. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Rom.  v.  i) :  Being  justified 
therefore  by  faith,  let  us  have  peace  with  God. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  3)  a  movement  of  free- 
will is  required  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly,  inas- 
much as  man's  mind  is  moved  by  God.  Now  God  moves 
man's  soul  by  turning  it  to  Himself  according  to  Ps.  Ixxxiv.  7 
(Septuagint) :  Thou  wilt  turn  us,  0  God,  and  bring  its  to  life. 
Hence  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  a  movement  of 
the  mind  is  required,  by  which  it  is  turned  to  God.  Now 
the  first  turning  to  God  is  by  faith,  according  to  Heb.  xi.  6: 
He  that  conieth  to  God  must  believe  that  He  is.  Hence  a 
movement  of  faith  is  required  for  the  justification  of  the 
ungodly. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  movement  of  faith  is  not  perfect  unless 
it  is  quickened  by  charity;  hence  in  the  justification  of  the 
ungodly,  a  movement  of  charity  is  infused  together  with  the 
movement  of  faith.  Now  free-will  is  moved  to  God  by 
being  subject  to  Him ;  hence  an  act  of  filial  fear  and  an  act 
of  humility  also  concur.  For  it  may  happen  that  one  and 
the  same  act  of  free-will  springs  from  different  virtues,  when 
one  commands  and  another  is  commanded,  inasmuch  as 
the  act  may  be  ordained  to  various  ends.  But  the  act  of 
mercy  counteracts  sin  either  by  way  of  satisfying  for  it, 
and  thus  it  follows  justification;  or  by  way  of  preparation, 
inasmuch  as  the  merciful  obtain  mercy;  and  thus  it  can 
either  precede  justification,  or  concur  with  the  other  virtues 
towards  justification,  inasmuch  as  mercy  is  included  in  the 
love  of  our  neighbour. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  By  natural  knowledge  a  man  is  not  turned 
to  God,  according  as  He  is  the  object  of  beatitude  and  the 
cause  of  justification.  Hence  such  knowledge  does  not 
suffice  for  justification.  But  the  gift  of  wisdom  presupposes 
the  knowledge  of  faith,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXVIIL,  A.  4, 
ad-^). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  iv.  5),  to  him  that 
.  .  .  believeth  in  Him  that  justifieth  the  ungodly  his  faith  is 


Q  113.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  388 

reputed  to  justice,  according  to  the  purpose  of  the  grace  of  God. 
Hence  it  is  clear  that  in  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  an 
act  of  faith  is  required  in  order  that  a  man  may  believe  that 
God  justifies  man  through  the  mystery  of  Christ. 


Fifth  Article. 

whether  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  there 
is  required  a  movement  of  the  free-will  towards 

SIN  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article: — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  no  movement  of  the  free-will 
towards  sin  is  required  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly. 
For  charity  alone  suffices  to  take  away  sin,  according  to 
Prov.  X.  12:  Charity  covereth  all  sins.  Now  the  object  of 
charity  is  not  sin.  Therefore  for  this  justification  of  the 
imgodly  no  movement  of  the  free-will  towards  sin  is  required. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  whoever  is  tending  onward,  ought  not 
to  look  back,  according  to  Philip,  iii.  13,  14:  Forgetting  the 
things  that  are  behind,  and  stretching  forth  myself  to  those 
that  are  before,  I  press  towards  the  mark,  to  the  prize  of  the 
supernal  vocation.  But  whoever  is  stretching  forth  to 
righteousness  has  his  sins  behind  him.  Hence  he  ought  to 
forget  them,  and  not  stretch  forth  to  them  by  a  movement  of 
his  free-will. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  in  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  one 
sin  is  not  remitted  without  another,  for  it  is  irreverent  to 
expect  half  a  pardon  from  God  (Cap.,  Sunt  plures:  Dist.  iii. 
De  Poenit.).  Hence,  in  the  justification  of  the  ungodly, 
if  man's  free-will  must  move  against  sin,  he  ought  to  think  of 
all  his  sins.  But  this  is  unseemly,  both  because  a  great 
space  of  time  would  be  required  for  such  thought,  and 
because  a  man  could  not  obtain  the  forgiveness  of  such  sins 
as  he  had  forgotten.  Hence  for  the  justification  of  the 
ungodly  no  movement  of  the  free-will  is  required. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  (Ps.  xxxi.  5) :  /  will  confess 
against  myself  my  injustice  to  the  Lord ;  and  Thou  hast  for- 
given the  wickedness  of  my  sin. 


389  THE  EFFFXTS  OF  GRACE     Q.  113  Art  5 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  the  justification  of 
the  ungodly  is  a  certain  movement  whereby  the  human 
mind  is  moved  by  God  from  the  state  of  sin  to  the  state  of 
justice.  Hence  it  is  necessary  for  the  human  mind  to  regard 
both  extremes  by  an  act  of  free-will,  as  a  body  in  local  move- 
ment is  related  to  both  terms  of  the  movement.  Now  it 
is  clear  that  in  local  movement  the  moving  body  leaves 
the  term  whence  and  nears  the  term  nDhereto.  Hence 
the  human  mind  whilst  it  is  being  justified,  must,  by  a  move- 
ment of  its  free-will  withdraw  from  sin  and  draw  near  to 
justice. 

Now  to  withdraw  from  sin  and  to  draw  near  to  justice,  in^ 
an  act  of  free-will,  means  detestation  and  desire.  For  Augus- 
tine says  on  the  words  the  hireling  flecth,  etc.  (John  x.  12): 
Our  emotions  are  the  movements  of  our  soul;  joy  is  the  soul's 
outpouring;  fear  is  the  soul's  flight;  your  soul  goes  forward 
when  you  seek;  your  soul  flees,  when  you  are  afraid.  Hence 
in  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  there  must  be  two  acts 
of  the  free-will — one,  whereby  it  tends  to  God's  justice;  the 
other  whereby  it  hates  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  It  belongs  to  the  same  virtue  to  seek  one 
contrary  and  to  avoid  the  other;  and  hence,  as  it  belongs  to 
charity  to  love  God,  so  likewise,  to  detest  sin  whereby  the 
soul  is  separated  from  God. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  A  man  ought  not  to  return  to  those  things 
that  are  behind,  by  loving  them;  but,  for  that  matter,  he 
ought  to  forget  them,  lest  he  be  drawn  to  them.  Yet  he  ought 
to  recall  them  to  mind,  in  order  to  detest  them ;  for  this 
is  to  ily  from  them. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Previous  to  justification  a  man  must  detest V 
each  sin  he  remembers  to  have  committed,  and  from  this 
remembrance  the  soul  goes  on  to  have  a  general  movement 
of  detestation  with  regard  to  all  sins  committed,  in  which 
are  included  such  sins  as  have  been  forgotten.  For  a  man 
is  then  in  such  a  frame  of  mind  that  he  would  be  sorry 
even  for  those  he  does  not  remember,  if  they  w'ere  present 
to  his  memory;  and  this  movement  co-operates  in  his  justifi- 
cation. 


Q.  T13.  Art.  0     THE  "  SUMMA  TTTEOLOrxICA  "  390 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  the  remission  of  sins  ought  to  be  reckoned 
amongst  the  things  required  for  justification  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  remission  of  sins  ought  not 
to  be  reckoned  amongst  the  things  required  for  justification. 
For  the  substance  of  a  thing  is  not  reckoned  together  with 
those  that  are  required  for  a  thing;  thus  a  man  is  not  reck- 
oned together  with  his  body  and  soul.  But  the  justifica- 
tion of  the  ungodly  is  itself  the  remission  of  sins,  as  stated 
above  (A.  i).  Therefore  the  remission  of  sins  ought  not  to 
be  reckoned  amongst  the  things  required  for  the  justifica- 
tion of  the  ungodly. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  infusion  of  grace  and  remission  of  sins 
are  the  same ;  as  illumination  and  expulsion  of  darkness  are 
the  same.  But  a  thing  ought  not  to  be  reckoned  together 
with  itself;  for  unity  is  opposed  to  multitude.  Therefore 
the  remission  of  sins  ought  not  to  be  reckoned  with  the 
infusion  of  grace. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  remission  of  sin  follows  as  effect  from 
cause,  from  the  free-will's  movement  towards  God  and  sin; 
since  it  is  by  faith  and  contrition  that  sin  is  forgiven.  But 
an  effect  ought  not  to  be  reckoned  with  its  cause;  since 
things  thus  enumerated  together,  and,  as  it  were,  con- 
divided,  are  by  nature  simultaneous.  Hence  the  remission 
of  sins  ought  not  to  be  reckoned  with  the  things  required 
for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly. 

On  the  contrary,  In  reckoning  what  is  required  for  a  thing 
we  ought  not  to  pass  over  the  end,  which  is  the  chief  part 
of  everything.  Now  the  remission  of  sins  is  the  end  of  the 
justification  of  the  ungodly;  for  it  is  written  (Isa.  xxvii.  9): 
This  is  all  the  fruit,  that  the  sin  thereof  should  he  taken  away. 
Hence  the  remission  of  sins  ought  to  be  reckoned  amongst 
the  things  required  for  justification. 

I  ansi^)er  that,  There  are  four  things  which  are  accounted 
to  be  necessary  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly,  viz.,  the 
infusion  of  grace,  the  movement  of  the  free-will  towards 


391  THE  EFFFXTS  OF  GRACE    Q.iivArt.  6 

God  by  faith,  the  movement  of  the  free-will  towards  sin, 
and  the  remission  of  sins.  The  reason  for  this  is  that,  as 
stated  above  (A.  i),  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  a 
movement  whereby  the  soul  is  moved  by  God  from  a  state 
of  sin  to  a  state  of  justice.  Now  in  the  movement  whereby 
one  thing  is  moved  by  another,  three  things  are  required : — 
first,  the  motion  of  the  mover;  secondly,  the  movement  of 
the  moved ;  thirdly,  the  consummation  of  the  movement,  or 
the  attainment  of  the  end.  On  the  part  of  the  Divine 
motion,  there  is  the  infusion  of  grace;  on  the  part  of  the 
free-will  which  is  moved,  there  are  two  movements, — of 
departure  from  the  term  whence,  and  of  approach  to  the 
teim  whereto  ;  but  the  consummation  of  the  movement  or 
the  attainment  of  the  end  of  the  movement  is  implied  in 
the  remission  of  sins;  for  in  this  is  the  justification  of  the 
ungodly  completed. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  called  the 
remission  of  sins,  even  as  every  movement  has  its  species 
from  its  term.  Nevertheless,  many  other  things  are  re- 
quired in  order  to  reach  the  term,  as  stated  above  (A.  5). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  infusion  of  grace  and  the  remission  of 
sin  may  be  considered  in  two  ways: — First,  with  respect  to 
the  substance  of  the  act,  and  thus  they  are  the  same;  for 
by  the  same  act  God  bestows  grace  and  remits  sin.  Secondly, 
they  may  be  considered  on  the  part  of  the  objects ;  and  thus 
they  differ  by  the  difference  between  guilt,  which  is  taken 
away,  and  grace,  which  is  infused;  just  as  in  natural  things 
generation  and  corruption  differ,  although  the  generation  of 
one  thing  is  the  corruption  of  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  enumeration  is  not  the  division  of  a 
genus  into  its  species,  in  which  the  things  enumerated  must 
be  simultaneous;  but  it  is  a  division  of  the  things  required 
for  the  completion  of  anything;  and  in  this  enumeration 
we  may  have  what  precedes  and  what  follows,  since  some 
of  the  principles  and  parts  of  a  composite  thing  may  precede 
and  some  follow. 


g.  T 13.  Art.  7     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  392 

Seventh  Article. 

whether  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  takes 
place  in  an  instant  or  successively  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  justification  of  the  ungodly 
does  not  take  place  in  an  instant,  but  successively,  since,  as 
already  stated  (A.  3),  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly 
there  is  required  a  movement  of  free-will.  Now  the  act  of 
the  free-will  is  choice,  which  requires  the  deliberation  of 
counsel,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XIII.,  A.  i).  Hence,  since 
deliberation  implies  a  certain  reasoning  process,  and  this 
implies  succession,  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  would 
seem  to  be  successive. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  free-will's  movement  is  not  without 
actual  consideration.  But  it  is  impossible  to  understand 
many  things  actually  and  at  once,  as  stated  above  (P.  I., 
Q.  LXXXV.,  A.  4).  Hence,  since  for  the  justification  of 
the  ungodly  there  is  required  a  movement  of  the  free-will 
towards  several  things,  riz.,  towards  God  and  towards  sin, 
it  would  seem  impossible  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly 
to  be  in  an  instant. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  a  form  that  may  be  greater  or  less,  e.g., 
blackness  or  whiteness,  is  received  successively  by  its  sub- 
ject. Now  grace  may  be  greater  or  less,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXII.,  A.  4).  Hence  it  is  not  received  suddenly  by  its 
subject.  Therefore,  seeing  that  the  infusion  of  grace  is 
required  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly,  it  would  seem 
that  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  cannot  be  in  an  instant. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  the  free-wall's  movement,  which  co- 
operates in  justification,  is  meritorious ;  and  hence  it  must 
proceed  from  grace,  without  which  there  is  no  merit,  as  we 
shall  state  further  on  (Q.  CXIV.,  A.  2).  Now  a  thing 
receives  its  form  before  operating  by  this  form.  Hence 
grace  is  first  infused,  and  then  the  free-will  is  moved  towards 
God  and  to  detest  sin.  Hence  justification  is  not  all  at 
once. 

Ohj.  5.  Further,  if  grace  is  infused  into  the  soul,  there 


393  THE  EFFFXTS  OF  (iRACE      Q.  113.  Art  7 

must  be  an  instant  when  it  iirst  dwells  in  the  soul;  so,  too, 
if  sin  is  forgiven  there  must  be  a  last  instant  that  man  is  in 
sin.  But  it  cannot  be  the  same  instant,  otherwise  oppo- 
sites  would  be  in  the  same  simultaneously.  Hence  they 
must  be  two  successive  instants;  between  which  there  must 
be  time,  as  the  Philosopher  says  [Phys.  vi.).  Therefore  the 
justification  of  the  ungodly  takes  place  not  all  at  once,  but 
successively. 

On  the  contrary.  The  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  caused 
by  the  justifying  grace  of  the  Holy  Spirit.  Now  the  Holy 
Spirit  comes  to  men's  minds  suddenly,  according  to  Acts 
ii.  2:  And  suddenly  there  came  a  sound  from  heaven  as  of  a 
mighty  wind  coming,  upon  which  the  gloss  says  that  the 
grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost  knows  no  tardy  efforts.  Hence  the 
justification  of  the  ungodly  is  not  successive,  but  instan- 
taneous. 

/  answer  that,  The  entire  justification  of  the  ungodly  con- 
sists as  to  its  origin  in  the  infusion  of  grace.  For  it  is  by 
grace  that  free-will  is  moved  and  sin  is  remitted.  Now  the 
infusion  of  grace  takes  place  in  an  instant  and  without 
succession.  And  the  reason  of  this  is  that  if  a  form  be  not 
suddenly  impressed  upon  its  subject,  it  is  either  because 
that  subject  is  not  disposed,  or  because  the  agent  needs  time 
to  dispose  the  subject.  Hence  we  see  that  immediately  the 
matter  is  disposed  by  a  preceding  alteration,  the  substantial 
form  accrues  to  the  matter;  thus  because  the  atmosphere  of 
itself  is  disposed  to  receive  light,  it  is  suddenly  illuminated 
by  a  body  actually  luminous.  Now  it  was  stated  (0.  CXH., 
A.  2)  that  God,  in  order  to  infuse  grace  into  the  soul,  needs 
no  disposition,  save  what  He  Himself  has  made.  And 
sometimes  this  sufficient  disposition  for  the  reception  of 
grace  He  makes  suddenly,  sometimes  gradually  and  suc- 
cessively, as  stated  above  (0.  CXH.,  A.  2,  ad  2).  For  the 
reason  why  a  natural  agent  cannot  suddenly  dispose  matter 
is  that  in  the  matter  there  is  a  resistant  which  has  some 
disproportion  with  the  power  of  the  agent;  and  hence  we 
see  that  the  stronger  the  agent,  the  more  speedil}^  is  the 
matter   disposed.     Therefore,    since    the    Divine    power   is 


Q.  IT3.  Art.  7     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  394 

infinite,  it  can  suddenly  dispose  any  matter  whatsoever  to 
its  form;  and  much  more  man's  free-will,  whose  movement 
is  by  nature  instantaneous.  Therefore  the  justification  of 
the  ungodly  by  God  takes  place  in  an  instant. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  movement  of  the  free-will,  which  con- 
curs  in  the  justification  of  the  ungodly,  is  a  consent  to 
detest  sin,  and  to  draw  near  to  God ;  and  this  consent  takes 
place  suddenly.  Sometimes,  indeed,  it  happens  that  de- 
liberation precedes,  yet  this  is  not  of  the  substance  of 
justification,  but  a  way  to  justification;  as  local  movement 
is  a  way  to  illumination,  and  alteration  to  generation. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  stated  above  (P.  L,  Q.  LXXXV.,  A.  5), 
there  is  nothing  to  prevent  two  things  being  understood  at 
once,  in  so  far  as  they  are  somehow  one;  thus  we  understand 
the  subject  and  predicate  together,  inasmuch  as  they  are 
united  in  the  order  of  one  affirmation.  And  in  the  same 
manner  can  the  free-will  be  moved  to  two  things  at  once  in 
so  far  as  one  is  ordained  to  the  other.  Now  the  free-will's 
movement  towards  sin  is  ordained  to  the  free-will's  move- 
ment towards  God,  since  a  man  detests  sin,  as  contrary  to 
God,  to  Whom  he  wishes  to  cling.  Hence  in  the  justifica- 
tion of  the  ungodly  the  free-will  simultaneously  detests  sin 
and  turns  to  God,  even  as  a  body  approaches  one  point  and 
withdraws  from  another  simultaneously. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  reason  why  a  form  is  not  received 
instantaneously  in  the  matter  is  not  the  fact  that  it  can 
inhere  more  or  less;  for  thus  the  light  would  not  be  sud- 
denly received  in  the  air,  which  can  be  illumined  more  and 
less.  But  the  reason  is  to  be  sought  on  the  part  of  the  dis- 
position of  the  matter  or  subject,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  The  same  instant  the  form  is  acquired,  the 
thing  begins  to  operate  with  the  form;  as  fire,  the  instant 
it  is  generated  moves  upwards,  and  if  its  movement  was 
instantaneous,  it  would  be  terminated  in  the  same  instant. 
Now  to  will  and  not  to  will, — the  movements  of  the  free- 
will,— are  not  successive,  but  instantaneous.  Hence  the 
justification  of  the  ungodly  must  not  be  successive. 

Reply  Obj.  5.    The  succession  of  opposites  in  the  same 


395  THE  EFFECTS  OF  GRACE     Q.  113.  Art  7 

subject  must  be  looked  at  differently  in  the  things  that  are 
subject  to  time  and  in  those  that  are  above  time.  For  in 
those  that  are  in  time,  there  is  no  last  instant  in  which  the 
previous  form  inheres  in  the  subject;  but  there  is  the  last 
time,  and  the  first  instant  that  the  subsequent  form  inheres 
in  the  matter  or  subject;  and  this  for  the  reason,  that  in 
time  we  are  not  to  consider  one  instant  as  immediately 
preceding  another  instant,  since  neither  do  instants  succeed 
each  other  immediately  in  time,  nor  points  in  a  line,  as  is 
proved  in  Physic,  vi.  But  time  is  terminated  by  an  instant. 
Hence  in  the  whole  of  the  previous  time  wherein  anything 
is  moving  towards  its  form,  it  is  under  the  opposite  form; 
but  in  the  last  instant  of  this  time,  which  is  the  first  instant 
of  the  subsequent  time,  it  has  the  form  which  is  the  term 
of  the  movement. 

But  in  those  that  are  above  time,  it  is  otherwise.  For  if 
there  be  any  succession  of  affections  or  intellectual  concep- 
tions in  them  (as  in  the  angels),  such  succession  is  not 
measured  by  continuous  time,  but  by  discrete  time,  even 
as  the  things  measured  are  not  continuous,  as  stated  above 
(P.  I.,  Q.  LIIL,  AA.  2,  3).  In  these,  therefore,  there  is  a 
last  instant  in  which  the  preceding  is,  and  a  first  instant  in 
which  the  subsequent  is.  Nor  must  there  be  time  in 
between,  since  there  is  no  continuity  of  time,  which  this 
would  necessitate. 

Now  the  human  mind,  which  is  justified,  is,  in  itself, 
above  time,  but  is  subject  to  time  accidentally,  inasmuch 
as  it  understands  with  continuity  and  time,  with  respect  to 
the  phantasms  in  which  it  considers  the  intelligible  species, 
as  stated  above  (P.  I.,  Q.  LXXXV.,  AA.  i,  2).  We  must, 
therefore,  decide  from  this  about  its  change  as  regards  the 
condition  of  temporal  movements,  i.e.,  we  must  say  that 
there  is  no  last  instant  that  sin  inheres,  but  a  last  time; 
whereas  there  is  a  first  instant  that  grace  inheres;  and  in 
all  the  time  previous  sin  inhered. 


Q.  113.  Art.  8     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  396 

Eighth  Article. 

whether  the  infusion  of  grace  is  naturally  the  first 
of  the  things  required  for  the  justification  of 
the  ungodly  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  infusion  of  grace  is  not  what 
is  naturally  required  first  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly. 
For  we  withdraw  from  evil  before  drawing  near  to  good, 
according  to  Ps.  xxxiii.  15 :  Turn  away  from  evil,  and  do 
good.  Now  the  remission  of  sins  regards  the  turning  away 
from  evil,  and  the  infusion  of  grace  regards  the  turning  to 
good.  Hence  the  remission  of  sin  is  naturally  before  the 
infusion  of  grace. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  disposition  naturally  precedes  the 
form  to  which  it  disposes.  Now  the  free-will's  movement 
is  a  disposition  for  the  reception  of  grace.  Therefore  it 
naturally  precedes  the  infusion  of  grace. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  sin  hinders  the  soul  from  tending  freely 
to  God.  Now  a  hindrance  to  movement  must  be  removed 
before  the  movement  takes  place.  Hence  the  remission  of 
sin  and  the  free-will's  movement  towards  sin  are  naturally 
before  the  infusion  of  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  The  cause  is  naturally  prior  to  its  effect. 
Now  the  infusion  of  grace  is  the  cause  of  whatever  is  re- 
quired for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly,  as  stated  above 
(A.  7).     Therefore  it  is  naturally  prior  to  it. 

/  answer  that.  The  aforesaid  four  things  required  for  the 
justification  of  the  ungodly  are  simultaneous  in  time,  since 
the  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  not  successive,  as  stated 
above  (A.  7) ;  but  in  the  order  of  natiu'e,  one  is  prior  to 
another;  and  in  their  natural  order  the  first  is  the  infusion 
of  grace;  the  second,  the  free-will's  movement  towards  God; 
the  third,  the  free-will's  movement  towards  sin;  the  fourth, 
the  remission  of  sin. 

The  reason  for  this  is  that  in  every  movement  the  motion 
of  the  mover  is  naturally  first;  the  disposition  of  the  matter, 
or  the  movement  of  the  moved,  is  second;  the  end  or  term 


397  THE  EFFECTS  OF  GRACE     Q  113.  Art.  8 

of  the  movement  in  which  the  motion  of  the  mover  rests, 
is  last.  Now  the  motion  of  God  the  mover  is  the  infusion 
of  grace,  as  stated  above  (A.  6) ;  the  movement  or  disposi- 
tion of  the  moved  is  the  free-will's  double  movement;  and 
the  term  or  end  of  the  movement  is  the  remission  of  sin,  as 
stated  above  (A.  6).  Hence  in  their  natural  order  the  first 
in  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  the  infusion  of  grace; 
the  second  is  the  free-will's  movement  towards  God;  the 
third  is  the  free-will's  movement  towards  sin,  for  he  who  is 
being  justified  detests  sin  because  it  is  against  God,  and 
thus  the  free-will's  movement  tow^ards  God  naturally  pre- 
cedes the  free-will's  movement  towards  sin,  since  it  is  its 
cause  and  reason;  the  fourth  and  last  is  the  remission  of 
sin,  to  which  this  transmutation  is  ordained  as  to  an  end, 
as  stated  above  (A A.  i,  6). 

Reply  Obj.  I.  The  withdrawal  from  one  term  and  approach 
to  another  may  be  looked  at  in  tw^o  ways: — first,  on  the 
part  of  the  thing  moved,  and  thus  the  withdraw^al  from  a 
term  naturally  precedes  the  approach  to  a  term,  since  in  the 
subject  of  movement  the  opposite  which  is  put  away  is  prior 
to  the  opposite  which  the  subject  moved  attains  to  by  its 
movement.  But  on  the  part  of  the  agent  it  is  the  other 
way  about,  since  the  agent,  by  the  form  pre-existing  in  it: 
acts  for  the  removal  of  the  opposite  form;  as  the  sun  by  its 
light  acts  for  the  removal  of  darkness,  and  hence  on  the 
part  of  the  sun,  illumination  is  prior  to  the  removal  of  dark- 
ness; but  on  the  part  of  the  atmosphere  to  be  illuminated, 
to  be  freed  from  darkness  is,  in  the  order  of  nature,  prior 
to  being  illuminated,  although  both  are  simultaneous  in 
time.  And  since  the  infusion  of  grace  and  the  remission  of 
sin  regard  God  Who  justifies,  hence  in  the  order  of  nature 
the  infusion  of  grace  is  prior  to  the  freeing  from  sin.  But 
if  we  look  at  what  is  on  the  part  of  the  man  justified,  it  is 
the  other  way  about,  since  in  the  order  of  nature  the  being 
freed  from  sin  is  prior  to  the  obtaining  of  justifying  grace. — 
Or  it  may  be  said  that  the  term  whence  of  justification  is 
sin;  and  the  term  whereto  is  justice;  and  that  grace  is  the 
cause  of  the  forgiveness  of  sin  and  of  the  obtaining  of  justice. 


Q.  113.  Art.  9     THE  "  SUMMA  THKOLOGICA  "  398 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  disposition  of  the  subject  precedes  the 
reception  of  the  form,  in  the  order  of  nature;  yet  it  follows 
the  action  of  the  agent,  whereby  the  subject  is  disposed. 
And  hence  the  free-will's  movement  precedes  the  reception 
of  grace  in  the  order  of  nature,  and  follows  the  infusion  of 
grace. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  the  Philosopher  says  [Phys.  ii.),  in  move- 
ments of  the  soul  the  movement  toward  the  speculative 
principle  or  the  practical  end  is  the  very  first,  but  in  exterior 
movements  the  removal  of  the  impediment  precedes  the 
attainment  of  the  end.  And  as  the  free-will's  movement  is 
a  movement  of  the  soul,  in  the  order  of  nature  it  moves 
towards  God  as  to  its  end,  before  removing  the  impediment 
of  sin. 

Ninth  Article. 

WHETHER    THE    JUSTIFICATION    OF     THE    UNGODLY    IS    GOD'S 

GREATEST   WORK  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Ninth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  justification  of  the  ungodly 
is  not  God's  greatest  work.  For  it  is  by  the  justification 
of  the  ungodly  that  we  attain  the  grace  of  a  wayfarer. 
Now  by  glorification  we  receive  heavenly  grace,  which  is 
greater.  Hence  the  glorification  of  angels  and  men  is  a 
greater  work  than  the  justification  of  the  ungodly. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  or- 
dained to  the  particular  good  of  one  man.  But  the  good  of 
the  universe  is  greater  than  the  good  of  one  man,  as  is  plain 
from  Ethic,  i.  Hence  the  creation  of  heaven  and  earth  is  a 
greater  work  than  the  justification  of  the  ungodly. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  to  make  something  from  nothing,  where 
there  is  nought  to  co-operate  with  the  agent,  is  greater 
than  to  make  something  with  the  co-operation  of  the  re- 
cipient. Now  in  the  work  of  creation  something  is  made 
from  nothing,  and  hence  nothing  can  co-operate  with  the 
agent;  but  in  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  God  makes 
something  from  something,  i.e.,  a  just  man  from  a  sinner, 
and  there  is  a  co-operation  on  man's  part,  since  there  is  a 


399  THE  EFFECTS  OF  GRACE     Q.  113.  Art.  9 

movement  of  the  free-will,  as  stated  above  (A.  3).  Hence 
the  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  not  God's  greatest  work. 

Oil  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  cxliv.  9) :  His  tender 
mercies  are  over  all  His  works,  and  in  a  Collect  (Tenth  Sunday 
after  Pentecost)  we  say:  0  God,  Who  dost  shoiv  forth  Thine 
all-niighti^icss  most  by  pardoning  and  having  mercy,  and 
Augustine,  expounding  the  words,  greater  than  these  shall 
he  do  (John  xiv.  12),  says  that  for  a  just  man  to  be  made 
from  a  sinner,  is  greater  than  to  create  heaven  and  earth. 

I  answer  that,  A  work  may  be  called  great  in  two  ways : — 
first,  on  the  part  of  the  mode  of  action,  and  thus  the  work 
of  creation  is  the  greatest  work,  wherein  something  is  made 
from  nothing;  secondly,  a  work  may  be  called  great  on 
account  of  what  is  made,  and  thus  the  justification  of  the 
ungodly,  which  terminates  at  the  eternal  good  of  a  share  in 
the  Godhead,  is  greater  than  the  creation  of  heaven  and 
earth,  wliich  terminates  at  the  good  of  mutable  nature. 
Hence,  when  Augustine  says  that  for  a  just  man  to  be  made 
from  a  sinner  is  greater  than  to,  create  heaven  and  earth,  he 
adds,  for  Heaven  and  earth  shall  pass  away,  but  the  justifica- 
tion of  the  ungodly  shall  endure. 

Again,  we  must  bear  in  mind  that  a  thing  is  called  great 
in  two  ways : — first,  in  absolute  quantity,  and  thus  the  gift 
of  glory  is  greater  than  the  gift  of  grace  that  sanctifies  the 
ungodly;  and  in  this  respect  the  glorification  of  the  just  is 
greater  than  the  justification  of  the  ungodly.  Secondly,  a 
thing  may  be  said  to  be  great  in  proportionate  quantity, 
and  thus  the  gift  of  grace  that  justifies  the  ungodly  is  greater 
than  the  gift  of  glory  that  beatifies  the  just,  for  the  gift  of 
grace  exceeds  the  worthiness  of  the  ungodly,  who  are  worthy 
of  punishment,  more  than  the  gift  of  glory  exceeds  the 
worthiness  of  the  just,  who  by  the  fact  of  their  justification 
are  worthy  of  glory.  Hence  Augustine  says:  Let  hi/n  that 
can,  judge  whether  it  is  greater  to  create  the  angels  just,  than 
to  justify  the  ungodly.  Certainly,  if  they  both  betoken  equal 
power,  one  betokens  greater  mercy. 

And  thus  the  reply  to  the  first  is  clear. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  good  of  the  universe  is  greater  than 


Q.  113.  Art.  10     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  400 

the  particular  good  of  one,  if  we  consider  both  in  the  same 
genus.  But  the  good  of  grace  in  one  is  greater  than  the 
good  of  nature  in  the  whole  universe. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  objection  rests  on  the  manner  of  acting, 
in  which  way  creation  is  God's  greatest  work. 


Tenth  Article. 

whether  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  a 
miraculous  work  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Tenth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  justification  of  the  ungodly 
is  a  miraculous  work.  For  miraculous  works  are  greater 
than  non-miraculous.  Now  the  justification  of  the  ungodly 
is  greater  than  the  other  miraculous  works,  as  is  clear  from 
the  quotation  from  Augustine  (A.  9).  Hence  the  justifica- 
tion of  the  ungodly  is  a  miraculous  work. 
'  Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  movement  of  the  will  in  the  soul  is 
like  the  natural  inclination  in  natural  things.  But  when 
God  works  in  natural  things  against  the  inclination  of  their 
nature,  it  is  a  miraculous  work,  as  when  He  gave  sight  to 
the  blind  or  raised  the  dead.  Now  the  will  of  the  ungodly 
is  bent  on  evil.  Hence,  since  God  in  justifying  a  man 
moves  him  to  good,  it  would  seem  that  the  justification  of 
the  ungodly  is  miraculous. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  as  wisdom  is  a  gift  of  God,  so  also  is 
justice.  Now  it  is  miraculous  that  anyone  should  suddenly 
obtain  wisdom  from  God  without  study.  Therefore  it  is 
miraculous  that  the  ungodly  should  be  justified  by  God. 

On  the  contrary,  Miraculous  works  are  beyond  natural 
power.  Now  the  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  not  beyond 
natural  power;  for  Augustine  says  (De  Freed.  Sanct.  v.)  that 
to  be  capable  of  having  faith  and  to  be  capable  of  having  charity 
belongs  to  man's  nature;  but  to  have  faith  and  charity  belongs 
to  the  grace  of  the  faithful.  Therefore  the  justification  of  the 
ungodly  is  not  miraculous. 

/  answer  that,  In  miraculous  works  it  is  usual  to  find  three 
things: — ilvQ first  is  on  the  part  of  the  active  power,  because 


401  THE  EFFECTS  OF  GRACE     Q.  113.  Art.  ro 

they  can  only  be  performed  by  Divine  power ;  and  they  are 
simply  wondrous,  since  their  cause  is  hidden,  as  stated  above 
(P.  I.,  Q.  CV.,  A.  7).  And  thus  both  the  justification  of 
the  ungodly  and  the  creation  of  the  world,  and,  generally 
speaking,  every  work  that  can  be  done  by  God  alone,  is 
miraculous. 

Secondly,  in  certain  miraculous  works  it  is  found  that 
the  form  introduced  is  beyond  the  natural  power  of  such 
matter,  as  in  the  resurrection  of  the  dead,  life  is  above 
the  natural  power  of  such  a  body.  And  thus  the  justifica- 
tion of  the  ungodly  is  not  miraculous,  because  the  soul  is 
naturally  capable  of  grace;  since  from  its  having  been 
made  to  the  likeness  of  God,  it  is  fit  to  receive  God  by  grace, 
as  Augustine  says,  in  the  above  quotation. 

Thirdly,  in  miraculous  works  something  is  found  besides 
the  usual  and  customary  order  of  causing  an  effect,  as  when 
a  sick  man  suddenly  and  beyond  the  wonted  course  of 
healing  by  nature  or  art,  receives  perfect  health;  and  thus 
the  justification  of  the  ungodly  is  sometimes  miraculous 
and  sometimes  not.  For  the  common  and  wonted  course 
of  justification  is  that  God  moves  the  soul  interiorly  and 
that  man  is  converted  to  God,  first  by  an  imperfect  con- 
version, that  it  may  afterwards  become  perfect;  because 
chanty  begun  merits  increase,  and  when  increased  merits 
perfection,  as  Augustine  says  [In  Epist.  Joan.,  Tract,  v.). 
Yet  God  sometimes  moves  the  soul  so  vehemently  that  it 
reaches  the  perfection  of  justice  at  once,  as  took  place  in 
the  conversion  of  Paul,  which  was  accompanied  at  the  same 
time  by  a  miraculous  external  prostration.  Hence  the 
conversion  of  Paul  is  commemorated  in  the  Church  as 
miraculous. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Certain  miraculous  works,  although  they 
are  less  than  the  justification  of  the  ungodly,  as  regards 
the  good  caused,  are  beyond  the  wonted  order  of  such 
effects,  and  thus  have  more  of  the  nature  of  a  miracle. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  is  not  a  miraculous  work,  whenever  a 
natural  thing  is  moved  contrary  to  its  inclination,  otherwise 
it  would  be  miraculous  for  water  to  be  heated,  or  for  a 

II.  3  26 


Q.  113.  Art.  10    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  402 

stone  to  be  thrown  upwards;  but  only  whenever  this  takes 
place  beyond  the  order  of  the  proper  cause,  which  naturally 
does  this.  Now  no  other  cause  save  God  can  justify  the 
ungodly,  even  as  nothing  save  fire  can  heat  water.  Hence 
the  justification  of  the  ungodly  by  God  is  not  miraculous  in 
this  respect. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  A  man  naturally  acquires  wisdom  and 
knowledge  from  God  by  his  own  talent  and  study.  Hence 
it  is  miraculous  when  a  man  is  made  wise  or  learned  outside 
this  order.  But  a  man  does  not  naturally  acquire  justify- 
ing grace  by  his  ow^n  action,  but  by  God's.  Hence  there  is 
no  parity. 


QUESTION  CXIV. 

OF  MERIT. 

{fii   Ten  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  merit,  which  is  the  effect  of  co-operat- 
ing grace ;  and  under  this  head  there  are  ten  points  of  inquiry : 
(i)    Whether   a   man    can    merit    anything    from    God  ? 

(2)  Whether  without  grace  anyone  can  merit  eternal  life  ? 

(3)  Whether  anyone  with  grace  may  merit  eternal  life 
condignly  ?  (4)  Whether  it  is  chiefly  through  the  instru- 
mentality of  charity  that  grace  is  the  principle  of  merit  ? 

(5)  Whether  a  man  may  merit  the  first  grace  for  himself  ? 

(6)  Whether  he  may  merit  it  for  someone  else  ?  (7)  Whether 
anyone  can  merit  restoration  after  sin  ?  (8)  Whether  he 
can  merit  for  himself  an  increase  of  grace  or  charity  ? 
(9)  Whether  he  can  merit  final  perseverance  ?  (10)  Whether 
temporal  goods  fall  under  merit  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  a  man  may  merit  anything  from  god  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  man  can  merit  nothing  from 
God.  For  no  one,  it  would  seem,  merits  by  giving  another 
his  due.  But  hy  all  the  good  we  do,  we  cannot  make  sufficient 
return  to  God,  since  yet  more  is  His  due,  as  also  the  Philosopher 
says  [Ethic,  viii.).  Hence  it  is  written  (Luke  xvii.  10): 
When  you  have  done  all  these  things  that  are  cojnmanded  you, 
say:  We  are  unprofitable  servants;  we  have  done  that  ivhich 
we  ought  to  do.  Hence  a  man  can  merit  nothing  from 
God. 

403 


Q.  114.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGTCA  "  4^4 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  it  would  seem  that  a  man  merits  nothing 
from  God,  by  what  profits  himself  only,  and  profits  God 
nothing.  Now  by  acting  well,  a  man  profits  himself  or 
another  man,  but  not  God,  for  it  is  written  (Job  xxxv.  7) : 
If  thou  do  justly,  what  shalt  thou  give  Him,  or  what  shall  He 
receive  of  thy  hand.  Hence  a  man  can  merit  nothing  from 
God. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  whoever  merits  anything  from  another 
makes  him  his  debtor;  for  a  man's  wage  is  a  debt  due  to  him. 
Now  God  is  no  one's  debtor;  hence  it  is  written  (Rom.  xi.  35) : 
Who  hath  first  given  to  Hijn,  and  recompense  shall  he  made 
him  ?     Hence  no  one  can  merit  anything  from  God. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Jer.  xxxi.  16) :  There  is  a 
reward  for  thy  work.  Now  a  reward  means  something 
bestowed  by  reason  of  merit.  Hence  it  would  seem  that  a 
man  may  merit  from  God. 

/  answer  that,  Merit  and  reward  refer  to  the  same,  for  a 
reward  means  something  given  anyone  in  return  for  work 
or  toil,  as  a  price  for  it.  Hence,  as  it  is  an  act  of  justice  to 
give  a  just  price  for  anything  received  from  another,  so  also 
is  it  an  act  of  justice  to  make  a  return  for  work  or  toil. 
Now  justice  is  a  kind  of  equality,  as  is  clear  from  the  Philo- 
/sopher  [Ethic,  v.),  and  hence  justice  is  simply  between  those 
that  are  simply  equal ;  but  where  there  is  no  simple  equality 
between  them,  neither  is  there  simple  justice,  but  there  may 
be  a  certain  manner  of  justice,  as  when  we  say,  '  right  of 
parents  or  lords,'  as  the  Philosopher  says,  in  the  same  book. 
And  hence  where  there  is  justice  simply,  there  is  the  character 
of  merit  and  reward  simply.  But  where  there  is  no  simple 
right,  but  only  relative,  there  is  no  character  of  merit  simply, 
but  only  relatively,  in  so  far  as  the  character  of  justice  is 
found  there ; .  since  the  child  merits  something  from  his  father 
and  the  slave  from  his  lord. 

Now  it  is  clear  that  between  God  and  man  there  is  the 
greatest  inequality:  for  they  are  infinitely  apart,  and  all 
man's  good  is  from  God.  Hence  there  can  be  no  justice 
of  absolute  equality  between  man  and  God,  but  only  of  a 
certain  proportion,  inasmuch  as  both  operate  after  their  own 


405  MERIT  Q.I  14.  Art.  I 

manner.  Now  the  manner  and  measure  of  human  virtue  is 
in  man  from  Ciod.  Hence  man's  merit  with  Ciod  only  exists 
on  the  presupposition  of  the  Divine  ordination,  so  that  man 
obtains  from  God,  as  a  reward  of  his  operation,  what  God 
gave  him  the  power  of  operation  for,  even  as  natural  things 
by  their  proper  movements  and  operations  obtain  that  to 
which  they  were  ordained  by  God ;  differently,  indeed,  since 
the  rational  creature  moves  itself  to  act  by  its  free-will,  hence 
its  action  has  the  character  of  merit,  which  is  not  so  in  other 
creatures. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Man  merits,  inasmuch  as  he  does  what  he 
ought,  by  his  free-will;  otherwise  the  act  of  justice  whereby 
anyone  discharges  a  debt  would  not  be  meritorious. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  God  seeks  from  our  goods  not  profit,  but 
glory,  i.e.,  the  manifestation  of  His  goodness;  even  as  He 
seeks  it  also  in  His  own  works.  Now  nothing  accrues  to 
Him,  but  only  to  ourselves,  by  our  worship  of  Him.  Hence 
we  merit  from  God,  not  that  by  our  works  anything  accrues 
to  Him,  but  inasmuch  as  we  work  for  His  glory. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Since  our  action  has  the  character  of  merit, 
only  on  the  presupposition  of  the  Divine  ordination,  it  does 
not  follow  that  God  is  made  our  debtor  simply,  but  His  own, 
inasmuch  as  it  is  right  that  His  will  should  be  carried  out. 

Second  Article, 
whether  anyone  without  grace  can  merit  eternal 

LIFE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  without  grace  anyone  can  merit 
eternal  life.  For  man  merits  from  God  what  he  is  divinely 
ordained  to,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  Now  man  by  his  nature 
is  ordained  to  beatitude  as  his  end;  hence,  too,  he  naturally 
wishes  to  be  blessed.  Hence  man  by  his  natural  endow- 
ments and  without  grace  can  merit  beatitude  which  is 
eternal  life. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  less  a  work  is  due,  the  more  meritori- 
ous it  is.     Now,  less  due  is  that  work  which  is  done  by  one 


Q.  114.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  406 

who  has  received  fewer  benefits.  Hence,  since  he  who  has 
only  natural  endowments  has  received  fewer  gifts  from 
God,  than  he  who  has  gratuitous  gifts  as  well  as  nature, 
it  would  seem  that  his  works  are  more  meritorious  with 
God.  And  thus  if  he  who  has  grace  can  merit  eternal  life 
to  some  extent,  much  more  may  he  who  has  no  grace. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  God's  mercy  and  liberality  infinitely  sur- 
pass human  mercy  and  liberality.  Now  a  man  may  merit 
from  another,  even  though  he  has  not  hitherto  had  his 
grace.  Much  more,  therefore,  would  it  seem  that  a  man 
without  grace  may  merit  eternal  life. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  vi.  23) :  The  grace 
of  God,  life  everlasting. 

I  answer  that,  Man  without  grace  may  be  looked  at  in 
two  states,  as  was  said  above  (Q.  CIX.,  A.  2) ; — the  first, 
a  state  of  perfect  nature,  in  which  Adam  was  before  his 
sin; — the  second,  a  state  of  corrupt  nature,  in  which  we  are 
before  being  restored  by  grace.  Therefore,  if  we  speak  of 
man  in  the  first  state,  there  is  only  one  reason  why  man 
cannot  merit  eternal  life  without  grace,  by  his  purely  natural 
endowments,  viz.,  because  man's  merit  depends  on  the 
Divine  pre-ordination.  Now  no  act  of  anything  whatso- 
ever is  divinely  ordained  to  anything  exceeding  the  propor- 
tion of  the  powers  which  are  the  principles  of  its  act ;  for  it  is 
a  law  of  Divine  providence  that  nothing  shall  act  beyond  its 
i/powers.  Now  everlasting  life  is  a  good  exceeding  the 
proportion  of  created  nature;  since  it  exceeds  its  know- 
ledge and  desire,  according  to  i  Cor.  ii.  9:  Eye  hath  not  seen, 
nor  ear  heard,  neither  hath  it  entered  into  the  heart  of  man.  And 
hence  it  is  that  no  created  nature  is  a  sufficient  principle 
of  an  act  meritorious  of  eternal  life,  unless  there  is  added 
',  a  supernatural  gift,  which  we  call  grace.  But  if  we  speak 
of  man  as  existing  in  sin,  a  second  reason  is  added  to  this, 
viz.,  the  impediment  of  sin.  For  since  sin  is  an  offence 
against  God,  excluding  us  from  eternal  life,  as  is  clear  from 
what  has  been  said  above  (Q.  LXXL,  A.  6;  Q.  CXHI.,  A.  2), 
no  one  existing  in  a  state  of  mortal  sin  can  merit  eternal 
life  unless  first  he  be   reconciled  to  God,  through  his  sin 


407  MERIT  o.  114.AKT2 

being  forgiven,  which  is  brought  about  by  grace.  For  the 
sinner  deserves  not  life,  but  death,  according  to  Rom.  vi.  23: 
The  wages  of  sin  is  death. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  God  ordained  human  nature  to  attain  the 
end  of  eternal  life,  not  by  its  own  strength,  but  by  the  help 
of  grace ;  and  in  this  way  its  act  can  be  meritorious  of  eternal 
life. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Without  grace  a  man  cannot  have  a  work 
equal  to  a  work  proceeding  from  grace,  since  the  more 
perfect  the  principle,  the  more  perfect  the  action.  Put  the 
objection  would  hold  good,  if  we  supposed  the  operations 
equal  in  both  cases. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  With  regard  to  the  first  reason  adduced,  the 
case  is  different  in  (lod  and  in  man.  For  a  man  receives 
all  his  power  of  well-doing  from  God,  and  not  from  man. 
Hence  a  man  can  merit  nothing  from  God  except  by  His 
gift,  which  the  Apostle  expresses  aptly  saying  (Rom.  xi.  35) : 
Who  hath  first  given  to  Him,  and  recompense  shall  be  made  to 
him  ?  But  man  may  merit  from  man,  before  he  has  received 
anything  from  him,  by  what  he  has  received  from  God. 

But  as  regards  the  second  proof  taken  from  the  impedi- 
ment of  sin,  the  case  is  similar  with  man  and  God,  since  one 
man  cannot  merit  from  another  whom  he  has  offended, 
unless  he  makes  satisfaction  to  him  and  is  reconciled. 


Third  Article. 

whether  a  man  in  grace  can  merit  eternal  life 

condignly  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — ■ 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  a  man  in  grace  cannot  merit 
eternal  life  condignly,  for  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  viii.  18) : 
The  sufferings  of  this  time  are  not  worthy  (condignue)  to  be 
compared  with  the  glory  to  come,  that  shall  be  revealed  in  us. 
But  of  all  meritorious  works,  the  sufferings  of  the  saints 
would  seem  the  most  meritorious.  Therefore  no  works  of 
men  are  meritorious  of  eternal  life  condignly. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  on  Rom.  vi.  23,  TJie  grace  of  God,  life 


g.  114.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  4(^8 

everlasting,  a  gloss  says:  He  might  have  truly  said'.  '  The 
wages  of  justice,  life  everlasting  ';  but  He  preferred  to  say  '  The 
grace  of  God,  life  everlasting,'  that  we  may  know  that  God  leads 
us  to  life  everlasting  of  His  own  mercy  and  not  by  our  merits. 
Now  when  anyone  merits  something  condignly  he  receives 
it  not  from  mercy,  but  from  merit.  Hence  it  would  seem 
that  a  man  with  grace  cannot  merit  life  everlasting  con- 
dignly. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  merit  that  equals  the  reward,  would 
seem  to  be  condign.  Now  no  act  of  the  present  life  can 
equal  everlasting  life,  which  surpasses  our  knowledge  and 
our  desire,  and,  moreover,  surpasses  the  charity  or  love  of  the 
wayfarer,  even  as  it  exceeds  nature.  Therefore  with  grace 
a  man  cannot  merit  eternal  life  condignly. 

hsri  On  the  contrary,  What  is  granted  in  accordance  with  a  fair 
judgment,  would  seem  a  condign  reward.  But  life  ever- 
lasting is  granted  by  God,  in  accordance  with  the  judgment 
of  justice,  according  to  2  Tim.  iv.  8:  As  to  the  rest,  there 
is  laid  up  for  me  a  crown  of  justice,  which  the  Lord,  the  just 
judge,  will  render  to  me  in  that  day.  Therefore  man  merits 
everlasting  life  condignly. 

/  answer  that,  Man's  meritorious  work  may  be  considered 
in  two  ways: — first,  as  it  proceeds  from  free-will;  secondly,  as 
it  proceeds  from  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost.  If  it  is 
considered  as  regards  the  substance  of  the  work.,  and  inas- 
much as  it  springs  from  free-will,  there  can  be  no  condignit}/ 
because  of  the  very  great  inequality.  But  there  is  con- 
gruity,  on  account  of  an  equality  of  proportion:  for  it  would 
seem  congruous  that,  if  a  man  does  what  he  can,  God  should 

[yf^  reward  him  according  to  the  excellence  of  his  power. 

^^  If,  however,  we  speak  of  a  meritorious  work,  inasmuch 
as  it  proceeds  from  the  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost  moving  us 
to  life  everlasting,  it  is  meritorious  of  life  everlasting  con- 
dignly. For  thus  the  value  of  its  merit  depends  upon  the 
power  of  the  Holy  Ghost  moving  us  to  life  everlasting 
according  to  John  iv.  14:  Shall  become  in  him  a  fount  of 
water  springing  up  into  life  everlasting.  And  the  worth  of 
the  work  depends  on  the  dignity  of  grace,  whereby  a  man, 


409  MERIT  Q.I  14.  Art.  4 

being  made  a  partaker  of  the  Divine  Nature,  is  adopted  as 
a  son  of  God,  to  whom  the  inheritance  is  due  by  right  of 
adoption,  according  to  Rom.  viii.  17:  If  sons,  heirs  also. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  Apostle  is  speaking  of  the  substance  of 
these  sufferings. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  This  saying  is  to  be  understood  of  the  first 
cause  of  our  reaching  everlasting  life,  viz.,  God's  mercy. 
But  our  merit  is  a  subsequent  cause. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  grace  of  the  Holy  Ghost  which  we  have 
at  present,  although  unequal  to  glory  in  act,  is  equal  to  it 
virtually  as  the  seed  of  a  tree,  wherein  the  whole  tree 
is  virtually.  So  likewise  by  grace  the  Holy  Ghost  dwells 
in  man;  and  He  is  a  sufficient  cause  of  life  everlasting; 
hence,  2  Cor.  i.  22,  He  is  called  the  pledge  of  our  inheritance. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  grace  is  the  principle  of  merit  through 
charity  rather  than  the  other  virtues  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  grace  is  not  the  principle  of 
merit  through  charity  rather  than  the  other  virtues.  For 
wages  are  due  to  work,  according  to  Matth.  xx.  8 :  Call  the 
labourers  and  pay  them  their  hire.  Now  every  virtue  is  a 
principle  of  some  operation,  since  virtue  is  an  operative 
habit,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LV.,  A.  2).  Hence  every  virtue 
is  equally  a  principle  of  merit. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  iii.  8) :  Every  man 
shall  receive  his  own  reward  according  to  his  labour.  Now 
charity  lessens  rather  than  increases  the  labour,  because  as 
Augustine  says  {De  Verbis  Dom.  Serm.  Ixx.  dc  Temp.),  love 
makes  all  hard  and  repulsive  tasks  easy  and  next  to  nothing. 
Hence  charity  is  no  greater  principle  of  merit  than  any 
other  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  greatest  principle  of  merit  would 
seem  to  be  the  one  whose  acts  are  most  meritorious.  But 
the  acts  of  faith  and  patience  or  fortitude  would  seem  to  be 
the  most  meritorious,  as  appears  in  the  martyrs,  who  strove 


Q.  114- Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  410 

for  the  faith  patiently  and  bravely  even  till  death.  Hence 
other  virtues  are  a  greater  principle  of  merit  than 
charity. 

On  the  contrary,  Our  Lord  said  (John  xiv.  21) :  He  that 
loveth  Me,  shall  he  loved  of  My  Father;  and  I  will  love  him  and 
will  manifest  Myself  to  him.  Now  everlasting  life  consists 
in  the  manifest  knowledge  of  God,  according  to  John  xvii.  3 : 
lliis  is  eternal  life  :  that  they  may  know  Thee,  the  only  true 
and  living  God.  Hence  the  merit  of  eternal  life  rests  chiefly 
with  charity. 

/  answer  that.  As  we  may  gather  from  what  has  been 
stated  above  (A.  i)  human  acts  have  the  nature  of  merit 
from  two  causes: — first  and  chiefly  from  the  Divine  ordina- 
tion, inasmuch  as  acts  are  said  to  merit  that  good  to  which 
man  is  divinely  ordained.  Secondly,  on  the  part  of  free- 
will, inasmuch  as  man,  more  than  other  creatures,  has  the 
power  of  voluntary  acts  by  acting  of  himself.  And  in  both 
these  ways  does  merit  chiefly  rest  with  charity.  For  we 
must  first  bear  in  mind  that  everlasting  life  consists  in  the 
enjoyment  of  God.  Now  the  human  mind's  movement  to 
the  fruition  of  the  Divine  good  is  the  proper  act  of  charity, 
whereby  all  the  acts  of  the  other  virtues  are  ordained  to 
this  end,  since  all  the  other  virtues  are  commanded  by 
charity.  Hence  the  merit  of  life  everlasting  pertains  first 
to  charity,  and  secondly,  to  the  other  virtues,  inasmuch  as 
their  acts  are  commanded  by  charity.  So,  likewise,  is  it 
manifest  that  what  we  do  out  of  love  we  do  most  willingly. 
Hence,  even  inasmuch  as  merit  depends  on  voluntariness, 
merit  is  chiefly  attributed  to  charity. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Charity,  inasmuch  as  it  has  the  last  end 
for  object,  moves  the  other  virtues  to  act.  For  the 
habit  to  which  the  end  pertains  always  commands  the 
habits  to  which  the  means  pertain,  as  was  said  above 
(Q.  IX.,  A.  I). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  work  can  be  toilsome  and  difficult  in  two 
ways: — first,  from  the  greatness  of  the  work,  and  thus  the 
greatness  of  the  work  pertains  to  the  increase  of  merit; 
and  thus  charity  does  not  lessen  the  toil — rather,  it  makes  us 


411  MERIT  g.  1 14.  Art.  5 

undertake  the  greatest  toils,  for  it  docs  great  things,  if  it 
exists,  as  Gregory  says  (Uoin.  in  Evang.  xxx.).  Secondly, 
from  the  defect  of  the  operator;  for  what  is  not  done  with  a 
ready  will  is  hard  and  difhcult  to  all  of  us,  and  this  toil 
lessens  merit  and  is  removed  by  charity. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  act  of  faith  is  not  meritorious  unless 
faith  .  .  .  workcth  by  charity  (Gal.  v.  6).  So,  too,  the  acts  of 
patience  and  fortitude  are  not  meritorious  unless  a  man 
does  them  out  of  charity,  according  to  i  Cor.  xhi.  3 :  //  / 
should  deliver  my  body  to  be  burned,  and  have  not  charity,  it 
profiteth  me  nothing. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  a  man  may  merit  for  himself  the  first  grace  ? 

Wc  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  man  may  merit  for  himself 
the  first  grace,  because,  as  Augustine  says  [Ep.  clxxxvi.), 
faith  merits  justification.  Now  a  man  is  justified  by  the 
first  grace.  Therefore  a  man  may  merit  the  first 
grace. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  God  gives  grace  only  to  the  worthy. 
Now,  no  one  is  said  to  be  worthy  of  some  good,  unless  he 
has  merited  it  condignly.  Therefore  we  may  merit  the  first 
grace  condignly. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  with  men  we  may  merit  a  gift  already 
received.  Thus  if  a  man  receives  a  horse  from  his  master, 
he  merits  it  by  a  good  use  of  it  in  his  master's  service.  Now 
God  is  much  more  bountiful  than  man.  Much  more,  there- 
fore, may  a  man,  by  subsequent  works,  merit  the  first  grace 
already  received  from  God. 

On  the  contrary,  The  nature  of  grace  is  repugnant  to 
reward  of  works,  according  to  I^om.  iv.  4:  Now  to  him  that 
worketh,  the  reward  is  not  reckoned  according  to  grace  but 
according  to  debt.  Now  a  man  merits  what  is  reckoned  to 
him  according  to  debt,  as  the  reward  of  his  works.  Hence  a 
man  may  not  merit  the  first  grace. 

/  answer  that,  The  gift  of  grace  may  be  considered  in  two 


Q.  114.  Art.  5    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  412 

ways: — first  in  the  nature  of  a  gratuitous  gift,  and  thus  it  is 
manifest  that  all  merit  is  repugnant  to  grace,  since  as  the 
Apostle  says  (Rom.  xi.  6),  if  by  grace,  it  is  not  now  by  works. — 
Secondly,  it  may  be  considered  as  regards  the  nature  of  the 
thing  given,  and  thus,  also,  it  cannot  come  under  the  merit 
of  him  who  has  not  grace,  both  because  it  exceeds  the  pro- 
portion of  nature,  and  because  previous  to  grace  a  man  in 
the  state  of  sin  has  an  obstacle  to  his  meriting  grace,  viz.,  sin. 
But  when  anyone  has  grace,  the  grace  already  possessed  can- 
not come  under  merit,  since  reward  is  the  term  of  the  work, 
but  grace  is  the  principle  of  all  our  good  works,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  CIX.).  But  if  anyone  merits  a  further  gratuitous 
gift  by  virtue  of  the  preceding  grace,  it  would  not  be  the 
first  grace.  Hence  it  is  manifest  that  no  one  can  merit  for 
himself  the  first  grace. 
^^-  Reply  Obj.  i.  As  Augustine  says  [Retract,  i.),  he  was 
deceived  on  this  point  for  a  time,  believing  the  beginning 
of  faith  to  be  from  us,  and  its  consummation  to  be  granted 
us  by  God;  and  this  he  here  retracts.  And  seemingly  it  is 
in  this  sense  that  he  speaks  of  faith  as  meriting  justification. 
But  if  we  suppose,  as  indeed  it  is  a  truth  of  faith,  that  the 
beginning  of  faith  is  in  us  from  God,  the  first  act  must  flow 
from  grace;  and  thus  it  cannot  be  meritorious  of  the  first 
grace.  Therefore  man  is  justified  by  faith,  not  as  though 
man,  by  believing,  were  to  merit  justification,  but  that,  he 
believes,  whilst  he  is  being  justified;  inasmuch  as  a  move- 
ment of  faith  is  required  for  the  justification  of  the  ungodly, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  CXIIL,  A.  4). 

Reply  Obj.  2.  God  gives  grace  to  none  but  to  the  worthy, 
not  that  they  were  previously  worthy,  but  that  by  His  grace 
He  makes  them  worthy.  Who  alone  can  make  him  clean  that 
is  conceived  of  unclean  seed  (Job  xiv.  4). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Man's  every  good  work  proceeds  from  the 
first  grace  as  from  its  principle;  but  not  from  any  gift  of 
man.  Consequently,  there  is  no  comparison  between  gifts 
of  grace  and  gifts  of  men. 


413  MERIT  Q.  114.  Art.  6 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  a  man  can  merit  the  first  grace  for 

ANOTHER  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  man  can  merit  the  first  grace 
for  another.  Because  on  Matth.  ix.  2,  Jesus  seeing  their 
faith,  etc.,  a  gloss  says:  How  much  is  our  personal  faith  worth 
with  God,  Who  set  such  a  price  on  another's  faith,  as  to  heal 
the  man  both  inwardly  and  outivardly  !  Now  inward  healing 
is  brought  about  by  grace.  Hence  a  man  can  merit  the 
first  grace  for  another. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  prayers  of  the  just  are  not  void,  but 
efficacious,  according  to  James  v.  16:  The  continued  prayer 
of  a  just  man  availeth  much.  Now  he  had  previously  said: 
Pray  one  for  another,  that  you  may  be  saved.  Hence,  since 
man's  salvation  can  only  be  brought  about  by  grace,  it 
seems  that  one  man  may  merit  for  another  his  first  grace. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  it  is  written  (Luke  xvi.  9) :  Make  unto 
you  friends  of  the  mammon  of  iniquity,  that  when  you  shall 
fail  they  7nay  receive  you  into  everlasting  dwellings.  Now  it 
is  through  grace  alone  that  anyone  is  received  into  ever- 
lasting dwellings,  for  by  it  alone  does  anyone  merit  ever- 
lasting life  as  stated  above  (A.  2;  Q.  CIX.,  A.  5).  Hence 
one  man  may  by  merit  obtain  for  another  his  first  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Jer.  xv.  i) :  If  Moses  and 
Samuel  shall  stand  before  Me,  My  soul  is  not  towards  this 
people — yet  they  had  great  merit  with  God.  Hence  it  seems 
that  no  one  can  merit  the  first  grace  for  another. 

/  answer  that.  As  shown  above  (AA.  i,  3,  4),  our  works 
are  meritorious  from  two  causes: — first,  by  virtue  of  the 
Divine  motion;  and  thus  we  merit  condignly; — secondly, 
according  as  they  proceed  from  free-will  in  so  far  as  we  do 
them  willingly,  and  thus  they  have  congruous  merit,  since 
it  is  congruous  that  when  a  man  makes  good  use  of  his 
power,  God  should  by  His  super-excellent  power  work  still 
higher  things.  And  therefore  it  is  clear  that  no  one  can 
merit  condignly  for  another  his  first  grace,  save  Christ  alone; 


Q.  1 14.  Art.  6     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  414 

since  each  one  of  us  is  moved  by  God  to  reach  life  ever- 
lasting through  the  gift  of  grace;  hence  condign  merit  does 
not  reach  beyond  this  motion.  But  Christ's  soul  is  moved 
by  God  through  grace,  not  only  so  as  to  reach  the  glory  of 
life  everlasting,  but  so  as  to  lead  others  to  it,  inasmuch  as 
He  is  the  Head  of  the  Church,  and  the  Author  of  human 
salvation,  according  to  Heb.  ii.  10:  Who  hath  brought  many 
children  into  glory  [to  perfect]  the  Author  of  their  salvation. 

But  one  may  merit  the  first  grace  for  another  congruously  ; 
because  a  man  in  grace  fulfils  God's  will,  and  it  is  congruous 
and  in  harmony  with  friendship  that  God  should  fulfil  man's 
desire  for  the  salvation  of  another,  although  sometimes  there 
may  be  an  impediment  on  the  part  of  him  whose  salvation 
the  just  man  desires.  And  it  is  in  this  sense  that  the 
passage  from  Jeremias  speaks. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  A  man's  faith  avails  for  another's  salvation 
by  congruous  and  not  by  condign  merit. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  impetration  of  prayer  rests  on  mercy, 
whereas  condign  merit  rests  on  justice;  hence  a  man  may 
impetrate  many  things  from  the  Divine  mercy  in  prayer, 
which  he  does  not  merit  in  justice,  according  to  Dan.  ix.  18: 
For  it  is  not  for  our  justifications  that  we  present  our  prayers 
before  Thy  face,  but  for  the  multitude  of  Thy  tender  mercies. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  poor  who  receive  alms  are  said  to 
receive  others  into  everlasting  dwellings,  either  by  impe- 
trating  their  forgiveness  in  prayer,  or  by  meriting  con- 
gruously by  other  good  works,  or  materially  speaking,  inas- 
much as  by  these  works  of  mercy,  exercised  towards  the 
poor,  we  merit  to  be  received  into  everlasting  dwellings. 

Seventfi  Article, 
whether  a  man  may  merit  restoration  after  a  fall  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  anyone  may  merit  for  himself 
restoration  after  a  fall.  For  what  a  man  may  justly  ask  of 
God,  he  may  justly  merit.  Now  nothing  may  more  justly 
be    besought    of    God  than  to  be  restored  after  a  fall,  as 


415  MERIT  Q.I  14.  Art  7 

Augustine  says,*  according  to  Ps.  Ixx.  9:  When  my  strength 
shall  fail,  do  not  Thou  forsake  me.  Hence  a  man  may  merit 
to  be  restored  after  a  fall. 

Ohj.  2.  Fm'ther,  a  man's  works  benefit  himself  more  than 
another.  Now  a  man  may,  to  some  extent,  merit  for 
another  his  restoration  after  a  fall,  even  as  his  first  grace. 
Much  more,  therefore,  may  he  merit  for  himself  restoration 
after  a  fall. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  when  a  man  is  once  in  grace  he  merits 
life  everlasting  by  the  good  works  he  does,  as  was  shown 
above  (A.  2;  Q.  CIX.,  A.  5).  Now  no  one  can  attain  life 
everlasting  unless  he  is  restored  by  grace.  Hence  it  would 
seem  that  he  merits  for  himself  restoration. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ezech.  xviii.  24) :  If  the  just 
man  turn  himself  away  from  his  justice  and  do  iniquity  .  .  . 
all  his  justices  which  he  hath  done  shall  not  he  rememhered. 
Therefore  his  previous  merits  will  nowise  help  him  to  rise 
again.  Hence  no  one  can  merit  for  himself  restoration  after 
a  fall. 

/  answer  that.  No  one  can  merit  for  himself  restoration 
after  a  future  fall,  either  condignly  or  congruously.  He 
cannot  merit  for  himself  condignly,  since  the  reason  of  this 
merit  depends  on  the  motion  of  Divine  grace,  and  this 
motion  is  interrupted  by  the  subsequent  sin;  hence  all 
benefits  which  he  afterwards  obtains  from  God,  whereby  he 
is  restored,  do  not  fall  under  merit — the  motion  of  the  pre- 
ceding grace  not  extending  to  them.  Again,  congruous 
merit,  whereby  one  merits  the  first  grace  for  another,  is 
prevented  from  having  its  effect  on  account  of  the  impedi- 
ment of  sin  in  the  one  for  whom  it  is  merited.  Much  more, 
therefore,  is  the  efficacy  of  such  merit  impeded  by  the 
obstacle  which  is  in  him  whcrtnerits,  and  in  him  for  whom  it  is 
merited ;  for  both  these  are  in  the  same  person.  And  there- 
fore a  man  can  nowise  merit  for  himself  restoration  after 
a  fall. 

Reply  Ohj.  1.  The  desire  whereby  we  seek  for  restoration 
after  a  fall  is  called  just,  and  likewise  the  prayer  whereby 

*  Cf.  Ennar.  i.     super  Ps.  Ixx. 


Q.  1T4.  Art.  8     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  416 

this  restoration  is  besought  is  called  just,  because  it  tends 
to  justice;  and  not  that  it  depends  on  justice  by  way  of 
merit,  but  only  on  mercy. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Anyone  may  congruously  merit  for  another 
his  first  grace,  because  there  is  no  impediment  (at  least,  on 
the  part  of  him  who  merits),  such  as  is  found  when  anyone 
recedes  from  justice  after  the  merit  of  grace. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Some  have  said  that  no  one  absolutely 
merits  life  everlasting  except  by  the  act  of  final  grace, — but 
only  conditionally,  i.e.,  if  he  perseveres.  But  it  is  unreason- 
able to  say  this,  for  sometimes  the  act  of  the  last  grace  is 
not  more,  but  less  meritorious  than  preceding  acts,  on 
account  of  the  prostration  of  illness.  Hence  it  must  be  said 
that  every  act  of  charity  merits  eternal  life  absolutely;  but 
by  subsequent  sin,  there  arises  an  impediment  to  the  pre- 
ceding merit,  so  that  it  does  not  obtain  its  effect;  just  as 
natural  causes  fail  of  their  effects  on  account  of  a  super- 
vening impediment. 

Eighth  Article, 
whether  a  man  may  merit  the  increase  of  grace  or 

CHARITY  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  man  cannot  merit  an  increase 
of  grace  or  charity.  For  when  anyone  receives  the  reward 
he  merited,  no  other  reward  is  due  to  him ;  thus  it  was  said 
of  some  (Matth.  vi.  2) :  They  have  received  their  reward. 
Hence,  if  anyone  were  to  merit  the  increase  of  charity  or 
grace,  it  would  follow  that,  when  his  grace  has  been  increased, 
he  could  not  expect  any  further  reward,  which  is  unfitting. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  nothing  acts  beyond  its  species.  But 
the  principle  of  merit  is  grace  or  charity,  as  was  shown 
above  (AA.  2,  4).  Therefore  no  one  can  merit  greater  grace 
or  charity  than  he  has. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  what  falls  under  merit  a  man  merits  by 
every  act  flowing  from  grace  or  charity,  as  by  every  such 
act  a  man  merits  life  everlasting.  If,  therefore,  the  increase 
of  grace  or  charity  falls  under  merit,  it  would  seem  that  by 


417  MERIT  Q.I  14.  Art.  8 

every  act  quickened  by  charity  a  man  would  merit  an  in- 
crease of  charity.  But  what  a  man  merits,  he  infallibly 
receives  from  God,  unless  hindered  by  subsequent  sin;  for 
it  is  written  (2  Tim.  i.  12) :  /  Imow  Whom  I  have  believed, 
and  I  am  certain  that  He  is  able  to  keep  that  which  I  have 
committed  unto  Him.  Hence  it  would  follow  that  grace  or 
charity  is  increased  by  every  meritorious  act ;  and  this  would 
seem  impossible  since  at  times  meritorious  acts  are  not  very 
fervent,  and  would  not  suffice  for  the  increase  of  charity. 
Therefore  the  increase  of  charity  does  not  come  under 
merit. 

O71  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  in  his  commentary  on 
John's  epistles  (cf.  Ep.  clxxxvi.)  that  charity  merits  increase, 
and  being  increased  merits  to  be  perfected.  Hence  the  increase 
of  grace  or  charity  falls  under  merit. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (AA.  6,  7),  whatever  the 
motion  of  grace  reaches  to,  falls  under  condign  merit. 
Now  the  motion  of  a  mover  extends  not  merely  to  the  last 
term  of  the  movement,  but  to  the  whole  progress  of  the 
movement.  But  the  term  of  the  movement  of  grace  is 
eternal  life ;  and  progress  in  this  movement  is  by  the  increase 
of  charity  or  grace  according  to  Prov.  iv.  18:  But  the  path 
of  the  just  as  a  shining  light,  goeth  forward  and  increaseth 
even  to  perfect  day,  which  is  the  day  of  glory.  And  thus  the 
increase  of  grace  falls  under  condign  merit. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Reward  is  the  term  of  merit.  But  there  is 
a  double  term  of  movement,  viz.,  the  last,  and  the  inter- 
mediate, which  is  both  beginning  and  term;  and  this  term 
is  the  reward  of  increase.  Now  the  reward  of  human 
favour  is  as  the  last  end  to  those  who  place  their  end  in  it; 
hence  such  as  these  receive  no  other  reward. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  increase  of  grace  is  not  above  the 
virtuality  of  the  pre-existing  grace,  although  it  is  above  its 
quantity,  even  as  a  tree  is  not  above  the  virtuality  of  the 
seed,  although  above  its  quantity. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  By  every  meritorious  act  a  man  merits  the 
increase  of  grace,  equally  with  the  consummation  of  grace 
which  is  eternal  life.     But  just  as  eternal  life  is  not  given 

II.  3  27 


Q.  114.  Art.  9     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  418 

at  once,  but  in  its  own  time,  so  neither  is  grace  increased 
at  once,  but  in  its  own  time,  viz.,  when  a  man  is  sufficiently 
disposed  for  the  increase  of  grace. 


Ninth  Article, 
whether  a  man  may  merit  perseverance  ? 

V/e  proceed  thus  to  the  Ninth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  anyone  may  merit  persever- 
ance. For  what  a  man  obtains  by  asking,  can  come  under 
the  merit  of  anyone  that  is  in  grace.  Now  men  obtain 
perseverance  by  asking  it  of  God;  otherwise  it  would  be 
useless  to  ask  it  of  God  in  the  petitions  of  the  Lord's  Prayer, 
as  Augustine  says  [De  Bono  Persev.  ii.).  Therefore  perse- 
verance may  come  under  the  merit  of  whoever  has 
grace. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  it  is  more  not  to  be  able  to  sin,  than  not 
to  sin.  But  not  to  be  able  to  sin  comes  under  merit,  for 
we  merit  eternal  life,  of  which  impeccability  is  an  essential 
part.  Much  more,  therefore,  may  we  merit  not  to  sin,  i.e., 
to  persevere. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  increase  of  grace  is  greater  than  perse- 
verance in  the  grace  we  already  possess.  But  a  man  may 
merit  an  increase  of  grace,  as  was  stated  above  (A.  8). 
Much  more,  therefore,  may  he  merit  perseverance  in  the 
grace  he  has  already. 

On  the  contrary,  What  we  merit,  we  obtain  from  God, 
imless  it  is  hindered  by  sin.  Now  many  have  meritorious 
works,  who  do  not  obtain  perseverance ;  nor  can  it  be  urged 
that  this  takes  place  because  of  the  impediment  of  sin, 
since  sin  itself  is  opposed  to  perseverance;  and  thus  if  any- 
one were  to  merit  perseverance,  God  would  not  permit  him 
to  fall  into  sin.  Hence  perseverance  does  not  come  under 
merit. 

/  answer  that,  Since  man's  free-will  is  naturally  flexible 
towards  good  and  evil,  there  are  two  ways  of  obtaining 
from  God  perseverance  in  good: — first,  inasmuch  as  free- 
will is  determined  to  good  by  consummate  grace,  which  will 


419  MERIT  Q.  114.  Art.  9 

be  in  glory  ;  secondly,  on  the  part  of  the  Divine  motion, 
which  inclines  man  to  good  unto  the  end.  Now,  as  ex- 
plained above  (AA.  6,  7,  8),  that  which  is  related  as  a  term 
to  the  free-will's  movement  directed  by  God  the  mover, 
falls  under  human  merit;  and  not  what  is  related  to  the 
aforesaid  movement  as  principle.  Hence  it  is  clear  that 
the  perseverance  of  glory  which  is  the  term  of  the  aforesaid 
movement,  falls  under  merit;  but  perseverance  of  the  way- 
farer does  not  fall  under  merit,  since  it  depends  solely  on 
the  Divine  motion,  which  is  the  principle  of  all  merit. 
Now  God  freely  bestows  the  good  of  perseverance,  on  whom- 
soever He  bestows  it. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  VVe  impetrate  in  prayer  things  that  we  do 
not  merit,  since  God  hears  sinners  who  beseech  the  pardon 
of  their  sins,  which  they  do  not  merit,  as  appears  from 
Augustine  on  John  ix.  31,  Now  we  know  that  God  doth  not 
hear  sinners,  otherwise  it  would  have  been  useless  for  the 
publican  to  say:  0  God,  he  merciful  to  me  a  sinner,  Luke 
xxiii.  13.  So  too  may  we  impetrate  of  God  in  prayer  the 
grace  of  perseverance  either  for  ourselves  or  for  others, 
although  it  does  not  fall  under  merit. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  perseverance  which  is  in  heaven  is 
compared  as  term  to  the  free-will's  movement;  not  so,  the 
perseverance  of  the  wayfarer,  for  the  reason  given  in  the 
body  of  the  article. 

In  the  same  way  may  we  answer  the  third  objection  which 
concerns  the  increase  of  grace,  as  was  explained  above. 

Tenth  Article. 
whether  temporal  goods  fall  under  merit  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Tenth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  temporal  goods  fall  under 
merit.  For  what  is  promised  to  some  as  a  reward  of  justice, 
falls  under  merit.  Now,  temporal  goods  were  promised  in 
the  Old  Law  as  the  reward  of  justice,  as  appears  from 
Deut.  xxviii.  Hence  it  seems  that  temporal  goods  fall  under 
merit. 


Q.  II4.ART.  lo    THE   "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  420 

Obj.  2.  Further,  that  would  seem  to  fall  under  merit, 
which  God  bestows  on  anyone  for  a  service  done.  But 
God  sometimes  bestows  temporal  goods  on  men  for  services 
done  for  Him.  For  it  is  written  (Exod.  i.  21) :  And  because 
the  midwives  feared  God,  He  built  them  houses;  on  which  the 
gloss  {Moral,  xviii.)  says  that  life  everlasting  might  have  been 
awarded  them  as  the  fruit  of  their  good-will,  but  on  account  of 
their  sin  of  falsehood  they  received  an  earthly  reward.  And 
it  is  written  (Ezech.  xxix.  18) :  The  King  of  Babylon  hath 
made  his  army  to  undergo  hard  service  against  Tyre  .  .  .  and 
there  hath  been  no  reward  given  him,  and  further  on:  And  it 
shall  be  wages  for  his  army.  ...  I  have  given  him  the  land  of 
Egypt  because  he  hath  laboured  for  me.  Therefore  temporal 
goods  fall  under  merit. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  as  good  is  to  merit  so  is  evil  to  demerit. 
But  on  account  of  the  demerit  of  sin  some  are  punished 
by  God  with  temporal  punishments,  as  appears  from  the 
Sodomites,  Gen.  xix.  Hence  temporal  goods  fall  under 
merit. 

Obj.  4.  On  the  contrary,  What  falls  under  merit  does  not 
come  upon  all  alike.  But  temporal  goods  regard  the  good 
and  the  wicked  alike;  according  to  Eccles.  ix.  2:  All  things 
equally  happen  to  the  just  and  the  wicked,  to  the  good  and  to 
the  evil,  to  the  clean  and  to  the  unclean,  to  him  that  offereth 
victims  and  to  him  that  despiseth  sacrifices.  Therefore  tem- 
poral goods  do  not  fall  under  merit. 

I  answer  that,  What  falls  under  merit  is  the  reward  or 
wage,  which  is  a  kind  of  good.  Now  man's  good  is  twofold — 
the  first,  simply;  the  second,  relatively.  Now  man's  good 
simply  is  his  last  end,  (according  to  Ps.  Ixxii.  27 :  But  it  is 
good  for  me  to  adhere  to  my  God),  and  consequently  what 
is  ordained  and  leads  to  this  end;  and  these  fall  simply  under 
merit.  But  the  relative,  not  the  simple,  good  of  man  is 
what  is  good  to  him  now,  or  what  is  a  good  to  him  re- 
latively; and  this  does  not  fall  under  merit  simply,  but 
relatively. 

Hence  we  must  say  that  if  temporal  goods  are  con- 
sidered  as    they  are   useful   for  virtuous  w^orks,   whereby 


421  MERIT  Q.  114.ART.  lo 

we  are  led  to  heaven,  they  fall  directly  and  simply  under 
merit,  even  as  increase  of  grace,  and  everything  whereby 
a  man  is  helped  to  attain  beatitude  after  the  first  grace. 
For  God  gives  men,  both  just  and  wicked,  enough  temporal 
goods  to  enable  them  to  attain  to  everlasting  life ;  and  thus 
these  temporal  goods  are  simply  good.  Hence  it  is  written 
(Ps.  xxxiii.  10) :  For  there  is  no  want  to  them  that  fear 
Him,  and  again,  Ps.  xxxvi.  25:  I  have  not  seen  the  just  for- 
saken, etc. 

But  if  these  temporal  goods  are  considered  in  themselves, 
they  are  not  man's  good  simply,  but  relatively,  and  thus 
they  do  not  fall  under  merit  simply,  but  relatively,  inasmuch 
as  men  are  moved  by  God  to  do  temporal  works,  in  which 
with  God's  help  they  reach  their  purpose.  And  thus  as 
life  everlasting  is  simply  the  reward  of  the  works  of  justice 
in  relation  to  the  Divine  motion,  as  stated  above  (AA.  3,  6), 
so  have  temporal  goods,  considered  in  themselves,  the  nature 
of  reward,  with  respect  to  the  Divine  motion,  whereby 
men's  wills  are  moved  to  undertake  these  works,  even  though, 
sometimes,  men  have  not  a  right  intention  in  them. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  As  Augustine  says  {Contra  Faust,  iv.),  in 
these  temporal  promises  were  figures  of  spiritual  things  to 
come.  For  the  carnal  people  were  adhering  to  the  promises 
of  the  present  life;  and  not  merely  their  speech  hut  even  their  life 
was  prophetic. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  These  rewards  are  said  to  have  been  divinely 
brought  about  in  relation  to  the  Divine  motion,  and  not  in 
relation  to  the  malice  of  their  wills,  especially  as  regards  the 
King  of  Babylon,  since  he  did  not  besiege  Tyre  as  if  wishing  to 
serve  God,  but  rather  in  order  to  usurp  dominion.  So,  too, 
although  the  midwives  had  a  good  will  with  regard  to  saving 
the  children,  yet  their  will  was  not  right,  inasmuch  as  they 
framed  falsehoods. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Temporal  evils  are  imposed  as  a  punishment 
on  the  wicked,  inasmuch  as  they  are  not  thereby  helped 
to  reach  life  everlasting.  But  to  the  just  who  are  aided  by 
these  evils  they  are  not  punishments  but  medicines  as  stated 
above  (Q.  LXXXVII.,  A.  8). 


Q.  114.  Art.  10    THE   "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  422 

Reply  Obj.  4.  All  things  happen  equally  to  the  good  and 
the  wicked,  as  regards  the  substance  of  temporal  good  or 
evil;  but  not  as  regards  the  end,  since  the  good  and  not  the 
wicked  are  led  to  beatitude  by  them. 

And  now  enough  has  been  said  regarding  morals  in 
general. 


Printed  in  England 


W  ON  rij 

OQt 


03 

to 


PONTIFICAL  INGTITtlTEOF  MEDIAEVAL  STUDIES 

59  QUEiLH'S  PARK  CRESCENT 

TORONTO-5,    CANADA 

5199  '