Skip to main content

Full text of "The "Summa theologica" of St. Thomas Aquinas"

See other formats


-co 

^M^av  ^_ 

z= 

=■0 

x=^ 

^c— 



=0 

=  o 

■ 

=  (£) 

=^C^- 

- 

CO 

ORBHW 


THE   -  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA 


II.  ii.  4 


HihU  ©bstai. 

Fr.   INNOCENTIUS  APAP,  O.P..  S.T.M. 
Censor  Theol. 

Imprimatur. 

EDUS.  CANONICUS  SURMONT 
Vicarios  Generalis. 

Westmonasterii. 


APPROBATIO  ORDINIS. 

|tihil  ©bsiat. 

Fr.  VINCENTIUS  McNABB,  O.P.,  S.T.M. 
Fr.  FABIANUS  DIX,  O.P.,   B.A. 

imprimatnr. 

Fr.  BEDA  JARRETT,  O.P.,  S.T.L.,  M.A., 
Prior  Provincialis  Anglic. 


LONDINI, 

Feb.  4  1922. 


THE 

SUMMA  THEOLOGICA 


55 


OF 


ST.  THOMAS  AQUINAS 


PART   II. 
(SECOND  PART) 

OO.  CI.—  CXL. 


LITERALLY    TRANSLATED    BY 


FATHERS   OF  THE  ENGLISH   DOMINICAN 

PROVINCE 


LONDON 

BURNS   OATES   &   WASHBOURNE    LTD. 

28  ORCHARD  STREET,  W.  i  8-10  PATERNOSTER  ROW,  E.C.  4 

BENZIGER  BROTHERS:   NEW  YORK,  CINCINNATI,  CHICAGO 
1922  All  rights  reserved 


CONTENTS 


QUESTION  PAGE 

CI.    OF    PIETY  ------  I 

CII.    OF    OBSERVANCE  -  -  -  -  -         IO 


Parts  of  Observance  and  Contrary  Vices 

cm.  of  dulia     -     -     -     -  -  -17 

civ.  of  obedience               -            -            -  -                   25 

cv.  of  disobedience         -            -            -  -  -      40 

cvi.  of  gratitude               -            -            -  -  "45 

cvii.  of  ingratitude           -            -  -  ~      57 

cviii.  of  vengeance              -            -            -  -  -      64 

cix.  of  truth          -             -            -            -  -                    76 

Opposed  to  Truth 

cx.  of  lying          -            -            -            -  -                   85 

cxi.  of  dissimulation  and  hypocrisy     -  -  "99 
cxii.  of  boasting    -              -----     109 

cxiii.  of  irony         -             -            -            -  -  -ii4 

cxiv.  of  friendliness          -            -            -  -  -il8 

Opposed  to  Friendliness 

cxv.  of  flattery                 -            -            -  -  -i23 

cxvi.  of  quarrelling           -            -            -  -  -     1 28 

cxvii.  of  liberality             -            -            .  -  -    1 32 

Opposed  to  Liberality, 

cxvih.  of  covetousness         -            -            -  -  -     1 44 

CXIX.    OF   PRODIGALITY                 -                 -                 -  -  -      l6l 

CXX.    OF   EQUITY           -                 -                -                 -  -  -1 68 

CXXI.    OF  THE   GIFT   OF   PIETY                  -                -  -  -      1 72 

CXXII.    OF    THE    PRECEPTS    OF   JUSTICE                    -  -  -       1 76 

V 


vi  CONTENTS 


TREATISE  ON  FORTITUDE 

QUESTION  PAGE 

CXXIII.    OF    FORTITUDE  -  193 

CXXIV.    OF   MARTYRDOM  .... 


Vices  opposed  to  Fortitude 


215 


CXXV.  OF  FEAR     -        -  227 

CXXVI.  OF  FEARLESSNESS   -----  235 

cxxvn.  of  (excessive)  daring        -  -  .  _  239 

Parts  of  Fortitude 

cxxviii.  of  the  parts  of  fortitude,  in  general  -  243 

cxxix.  of  magnanimity      -----  249 

cxxx.  of  presumption  opposed  to  magnanimity  -  268 

cxxxi.  of  ambition  ,,  ,,  „  -  273 

cxxxii.  of  vainglory  ,,  }j  „  277 

cxxxiii.  of  pusillanimity      „  „  „  288 

cxxxiv.  of  magnificence     -----  293 

cxxxv.  of  meanness  opposed  to  magnificence    -  -  302 

cxxxvi.  of  patience  -----  306 

cxxxvii.  of  perseverance  -  3i7 

cxxxviii.  of  the  vices  opposed  to  perseverance-  -  326 

cxxxix.  of  the  gift  of  fortitude  ...  330 

cxl.  of  the  precepts  of  fortitude     -  -  -  334 


THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA" 

SECOND    PART    OF    THE    SECOND    PART. 

QQ.   CI.-CXL 

QUESTION    CI. 

OF  PIETY. 
(In  Four  Articles.) 

After  religion  we  must  consider  piety,  the  consideration  of 
which  will  render  the  opposite  vices  manifest.  Accordingly 
four  points  of  inquiry  arise  with  regard  to  piety:  (i)  To 
whom  does  piety  extend  ?  (2)  What  does  piety  make  one 
offer  a  person  ?  (3)  Whether  piety  is  a  special  virtue  ? 
(4)  Whether  the  duties  of  piety  should  be  omitted  for  the 
sake  of  religion  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  piety  extends  to  particular  human 

individuals  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  piety  does  not  extend  to 
particular  human  individuals.  For  Augustine  says  (De 
Civ.  Dei  x.)  that  piety  denotes,  properly  speaking,  the  wor- 
ship of  God,  which  the  Greeks  designate  by  the  term  evcrefteia. 
But  the  worship  of  God  does  not  denote  relation  to  man, 
but  only  to  God.  Therefore  piety  does  not  extend  definitely 
to  certain  human  individuals. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Gregory  says  (Moral,  i.) :  Piety,  on  her 
day,  -provides  a  banquet,  because  she  fills  the  inmost  recesses  of 
the  heart  with  works  of  mercy.     Now  the  works  of  mercy  are 

II.  ii.  4  I 


Q.  101.  Aft.  i      THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  2 

to  be  done  to  all,  according  to  Augustine  (De  Doctr.  Christ,  i.). 
Therefore  piety  does  not  extend  definitely  to  certain  special 
persons. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  In  human  affairs  there  are  many  other 
mutual  relations  besides  those  of  kindred  and  citizenship,  as 
the  Philosopher  states  (Ethic,  viii.ii,  12),  and  on  each  of  them 
is  founded  a  kind  of  friendship,  which  would  seem  to  be  the 
virtue  of  piety,  according  to  a  gloss  on  2  Tim.  hi.  5,  Having 
an  appearance  indeed  of  piety  (Douay, — godliness).  Therefore 
piety  extends  not  only  to  one's  kindred  and  fellow-citizens. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  says  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  it  is 
by  piety  that  we  do  our  duty  towards  our  kindred  and  well- 
wishers  of  our  country  and  render  them  faithful  service. 

I  answer  that,  Man  becomes  a  debtor  to  other  men  in 
various  ways,  according  to  their  various  excellence  and  the 
various  benefits  received  from  them.  On  both  counts  God 
holds  first  place,  for  He  is  supremely  excellent,  and  is  for  us 
the  first  principle  of  being  and  government.  In  the  second 
place,  the  principles  of  our  being  and  government  are  our 
parents  and  our  country,  that  have  given  us  birth  and 
nourishment.  Consequently  man  is  debtor  chiefly  to  his 
parents  and  his  country,  after  God.  Wherefore  just  as  it 
belongs  to  religion  to  give  worship  to  God,  so  does  it  belong 
to  piety,  in  the  second  place,  to  give  worship  to  one's  parents 
and  one's  country. 

The  worship  due  to  our  parents  includes  the  worship  given 
to  all  our  kindred,  since  our  kinsfolk  are  those  who  descend 
from  the  same  parents,  according  to  the  Philosopher 
(Ethic,  viii.  12).  The  worship  given  to  our  country  includes 
homage  to  all  our  fellow-citizens  and  to  all  the  friends  of  our 
country.     Therefore  piety  extends  chiefly  to  these. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  greater  includes  the  lesser:  wherefore 
the  worship  due  to  God  includes  the  worship  due  to  our 
parents  as  a  particular.  Hence  it  is  written  (Malach.  i.  6) : 
If  I  be  a  father,  where  is  My  honour  ?  Consequently  the 
term  piety  extends  also  to  the  divine  worship. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  x.),  the 
term  piety  is  often  used  in  connection  with  works  of  mercy, 


3  PIETY  Q.xoi.Art.2 

in  the  language  of  the  common  people  ;  the  reason  for  which 
I  consider  to  be  the  fact  that  God  Himself  has  declared  that  these 
works  are  more  pleasing  to  Him  than  sacrifices.  This  custom 
has  led  to  the  application  of  the  word  "  pious  "  to  God  Himself. 
Reply  Obj.  3.  The  relations  of  a  man  with  his  kindred 
and  fellow-citizens  are  more  referable  to  the  principles  of 
his  toeing  than  other  relations :  wherefore  the  term  piety  is 
more  applicable  to  them. 

Second  Article, 
whether  piety  provides  support  for  our  parents  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  piety  does  not  provide  support 
for  our  parents.  For,  seemingly,  the  precept  of  the  decalogue, 
Honour  thy  father  and  thy  mother,  belongs  to  piety.  But 
this  prescribes  only  the  giving  of  honour.  Therefore  it  does 
not  belong  to  piety  to  provide  support  for  one's  parents. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  A  man  is  bound  to  lay  up  for  those 
whom  he  is  bound  to  support.  Now  according  to  the 
Apostle  (2  Cor.  xii.  14),  neither  ought  the  children  to  lay  up 
for  the  parents.  Therefore  piety  does  not  oblige  them  to 
support  their  parents. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Piety  extends  not  only  to  one's  parents, 
but  also  to  other  kinsmen  and  to  one's  fellow-citizens,  as 
stated  above  (A.  1.).  But  one  is  not  bound  to  support  all 
one's  kindred  and  fellow-citizens.  Therefore  neither  is  one 
bound  to  support  one's  parents. 

On  the  contrary,  Our  Lord  (Matth.  xv.  3-6)  reproved  the 
Pharisees  for  hindering  children  from  supporting  their 
parents. 

/  answer  that,  We  owe  something  to  our  parents  and 
fellow-citizens  in  two  ways:  essentially,  and  accidentally. 
We  owe  them  essentially  that  which  is  due  to  a  father  as 
such:  and  since  he  is  his  son's  superior  through  being  the 
principle  of  his  being,  the  latter  owes  him  reverence  and 
service.  Accidentally,  that  is  due  to  a  father,  which  it 
befits  him  to  receive  in  respect  of  something  accidental  to 


Q.  ioi.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  4 

him,  for  instance,  if  he  be  ill,  it  is  fitting  that  his 
children  should  visit  him  and  see  to  his  cure;  if  he  be  poor, 
it  is  fitting  that  they  should  support  him;  and  so  on  in  like 
instance,  all  of  which  come  under  the  head  of  service  due. 
Hence  Tully  says  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  piety  gives  both 
duty  and  homage  :  duty  referring  to  service,  and  homage  to 
reverence  or  honour,  because,  as  Augustine  says  (De  Civ. 
Dei.  x.),  we  are  said  to  give  homage  to  those  whose  memory 
or  presence  we  honour. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  According  to  Our  Lord's  interpretation 
(Matth.  xv.  3-6),  the  honour  due  to  our  parents  includes 
whatever  support  we  owe  them;  and  the  reason  for  this  is 
that  support  is  given  to  one's  father  because  it  is  due  to  him 
as  to  one  greater. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Since  a  father  stands  in  the  relation  of 
principle,  and  his  son  in  the  relation  of  that  which  is  from  a 
principle,  it  is  essentially  fitting  for  a  father  to  support  his 
son :  and  consequently  he  is  bound  to  support  him  not  only 
for  a  time,  but  for  all  his  life,  and  this  is  to  lay  by.  On  the 
other  hand,  for  the  son  to  bestow  something  on  his  father  is 
accidental,  arising  from  some  momentary  necessity,  wherein 
he  is  bound  to  support  him,  but  not  to  lay  by  as  for  a  long 
time  beforehand,  because  naturally  parents  are  not  the 
successors  of  their  children,  but  children  of  their  parents. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  Tully  says  (loc.  cit.),  we  owe  homage 
and  duty  to  all  our  kindred  and  to  the  well-wishers  of  our 
country ;  not,  however,  equally  to  all,  but  chiefly  to  our 
parents,  and  to  others  according  to  our  means  and  their 
personal  claims. 

Third  Article. 

whether  piety  is  a  special  virtue  distinct  from 

other  virtues  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  piety  is  not  a  special  virtue 
distinct  from  other  virtues.  For  the  giving  of  service  and 
homage  to  anyone  proceeds  from  love.  But  it  belongs  to 
piety.     Therefore  piety  is  not  a  distinct  virtue  from  charity. 


5  PIETY  Q.101.ART.3 

Obj.  2.  Further,  It  is  proper  to  religion  to  give  worship 
to  God.  But  piety  also  gives  worship  to  God,  according  to 
Augustine  (De  Civ.  Dei  x.).  Therefore  piety  is  not  distinct 
from  religion. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Piety,  whereby  we  give  our  country  wor- 
ship and  duty,  seems  to  be  the  same  as  legal  justice,  which 
looks  to  the  common  good.  But  legal  justice  is  a  general 
virtue,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  v.  1,  2).  There- 
fore piety  is  not  a  special  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  accounted  by  Tully  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.) 
as  a  part  of  justice. 

/  answer  that,  A  special  virtue  is  one  that  regards  an  object 
under  a  special  aspect.  Since,  then,  the  nature  of  justice 
consists  in  rendering  another  person  his  due,  wherever  there 
is  a  special  aspect  of  something  due  to  a  person,  there  is  a 
special  virtue.  Now  a  thing  is  indebted  in  a  special  way  to 
that  which  is  its  connatural  principle  of  being  and  govern- 
ment. And  piety  regards  this  principle,  inasmuch  as  it  pays 
duty  and  homage  to  our  parents  and  country,  and  to  those 
who  are  related  thereto.    Therefore  piety  is  a  special  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Just  as  religion  is  a  protestation  of  faith, 
hope  and  charity,  whereby  man  is  primarily  directed  to  God, 
so  again  piety  is  a  protestation  of  the  charity  we  bear 
towards  our  parents  and  country. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  God  is  the  principle  of  our  being  and  govern- 
ment in  a  far  more  excellent  manner  than  one's  father  or 
country.  Hence  religion,  which  gives  worship  to  God,  is  a 
distinct  virtue  from  piety,  which  pays  homage  to  our  parents 
and  country.  But  things  relating  to  creatures  are  trans- 
ferred to  God  as  the  summit  of  excellence  and  causality,  as 
Dionysius  says  (Div.  Norn,  i.) :  wherefore,  by  way  of  ex- 
cellence, piety  designates  the  worship  of  God,  even  as  God, 
by  way  of  excellence,  is  called  Our  Father. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Piety  extends  to  our  country  in  so  far  as  the 
latter  is  for  us  a  principle  of  being:  but  legal  justice  regards 
the  good  of  our  country,  considered  as  the  common  good : 
wherefore  legal  justice  has  more  of  the  character  of  a  general 
virtue  than  piety  has. 


Q.ioi.Art.4      THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  6 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  duties  of  piety  towards  one's  parents 
should  be  omitted  for  the  sake  of  religion  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  I.  It  seems  that  the  duties  of  piety  towards  one's 
parents  should  be  omitted  for  the  sake  of  religion.  For 
Our  Lord  said  (Luke  xiv.  26) :  If  any  man  come  to  Me,  and 
hate  not  his  father,  and  mother,  and  wife,  and  children,  and 
brethren,  and  sisters,  yea  and  his  own  life  also,  he  cannot  be 
My  disciple.  Hence  it  is  said  in  praise  of  James  and  John 
(Matth.  iv.  22)  that  they  left  their  nets  and  father,  and  fol- 
lowed Christ.  Again  it  is  said  in  praise  of  the  Levites 
(Deut.  xxxiii.  9):  Who  hath  said  to  his  father,  and  to  his 
mother :  I  do  not  know  you  ;  and  to  his  brethren :  I  know  you 
not ;  and  their  own  children  they  have  not  known.  These  have 
kept  Thy  word.  Now  a  man  who  knows  not  his  parents  and 
other  kinsmen,  or  who  even  hates  them,  must  needs  omit 
the  duties  of  piety.  Therefore  the  duties  of  piety  should 
be  omitted  for  the  sake  of  religion. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  It  is  written  (Luke  ix.  59,  60)  that  in 
answer  to  him  who  said :  Suffer  me  first  to  go  and  bury  my 
father,  Our  Lord  replied :  Let  the  dead  bury  their  dead:  but  go 
thou,  and  preach  the  kingdom  of  God.  Now  the  latter  pertains 
to  religion,  while  it  is  a  duty  of  piety  to  bury  one's  father. 
Therefore  a  duty  of  piety  should  be  omitted  for  the  sake 
of  religion. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  God  is  called  Our  Father  by  excellence. 
Now  just  as  we  worship  our  parents  by  paying  them  the 
duties  of  piety,  so  do  we  worship  God  by  religion.  There- 
fore the  duties  of  piety  should  be  omitted  for  the  sake  of 
the  worship  of  religion. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Religious  are  bound  by  a  vow  which 
they  may  not  break  to  fulfil  the  observances  of  religion. 
Now  in  accordance  with  those  observances  they  are  hin- 
dered from  supporting  their  parents,  both  on  the  score  of 
poverty,  since  they  have  nothing  of  their  own,  and  on  the 


7  PIETY  Q.  101.ART.4 

score  of  obedience,  since  they  may  not  leave  the  cloister 
without  the  permission  of  their  superior.  Therefore  the 
duties  of  piety  towards  one's  parents  should  be  omitted  for 
the  sake  of  religion. 

On  the  contrary,  Our  Lord  reproved  the  Pharisees 
(Matth.  xv.  3-6)  who  taught  that  for  the  sake  of  religion 
one  ought  to  refrain  from  paying  one's  parents  the  honour 
we  owe  them. 

/  answer  that,  Religion  and  piety  are  two  virtues.  Now 
no  virtue  is  opposed  to  another  virtue,  since  according  to 
the  Philosopher,  in  his  book  on  the  Categories  (Cap.  De 
Oppos.),  good  is  not  opposed  to  good.  Therefore  it  is  impossible 
that  religion  and  piety  mutually  hinder  one  another,  so  that 
the  act  of  one  be  excluded  by- the  act  of  the  other.  Now,  as 
stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  VII.,  A.  2:  Q.  XVIIL,  A.  3),  the  act 
of  every  virtue  is  limited  by  the  circumstances  due  thereto, 
and  if  it  overstep  them  it  will  be  an  act  no  longer  of  virtue, 
but  of  vice.  Hence  it  belongs  to  piety  to  pay  duty  and 
homage  to  one's  parents  according  to  the  due  mode.  But 
it  is  not  the  due  mode  that  man  should  tend  to  worship  his 
father  rather  than  God,  but,  as  Ambrose  says  on  Luke  xii.  52, 
the  piety  of  divine  religion  takes  precedence  of  the  claims  of 
kindred. 

Accordingly,  if  the  worship  of  one's  parents  take  one 
away  from  the  worship  of  God  it  would  no  longer  be  an  act 
of  piety  to  pay  worship  to  one's  parents  to  the  prejudice  of 
God.  Hence  Jerome  says  (Ep.  ad  Heliod.) :  Though  thou 
trample  upon  thy  father,  though  thou  spurn  thy  mother,  turn 
not  aside,  but  with  dry  eyes  hasten  to  the  standard  of  the 
cross;  it  is  the  highest  degree  of  piety  to  be  cruel  in  this  matter. 
Therefore  in  such  a  case  the  duties  of  piety  towards  one's 
parents  should  be  omitted  for  the  sake  of  the  worship  religion 
gives  to  God.  If,  however,  by  paying  the  services  due  to 
our  parents,  we  are  not  withdrawn  from  the  service  of  God, 
then  will  it  be  an  act  of  piety,  and  there  will  be  no  need  to 
set  piety  aside  for  the  sake  of  religion. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Gregory  expounding  this  saying  of  Our  Lord 
says  (Horn,  xxxvii.  in  Ev.)  that  when  we  find  our  parents  to 


Q.  ioi.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  8 

be  a  hindrance  in  our  way  to  God,  we  must  ignore  them  by 
hating  and  fleeing  from  them.  For  if  our  parents  incite  us  to 
sin,  and  withdraw  us  from  the  service  of  God,  we  must,  as 
regards  this  point,  abandon  and  hate  them.  It  is  in  this  sense 
that  the  Levites  are  said  to  have  not  known  their  kindred, 
because  they  obeyed  the  Lord's  command,  and  spared  not 
the  idolaters  (Exod.  xxxii.).  James  and  John  are  praised 
for  leaving  their  parents  and  following  our  Lord,  not  that 
their  father  incited  them  to  evil,  but  because  they  deemed  it 
possible  for  him  to  find  another  means  of  livelihood,  if  they 
followed  Christ. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Our  Lord  forbade  the  disciple  to  bury  his 
father  because,  according  to  Chrysostom  {Horn,  xxviii.  in 
Matth.),  Our  Lord  by  so  doing  saved  him  from  many  evils,  such 
as  the  sorrows  and  worries  and  other  things  that  one  anticipates 
under  these  circumstances.  For  after  the  burial  the  will  had 
to  be  read,  the  estate  had  to  be  divided,  and  so  forth:  but  chiefly, 
because  there  were  others  who  could  see  to  the  funeral.  Or, 
according  to  Cyril's  commentary  on  Luke  ix.,  this  disciple's 
■request  was,  not  that  he  might  bury  a  dead  father,  but  that  he 
might  support  a  yet  living  father  in  the  latter' s  old  age,  until  at 
length  he  should  bury  him.  This  is  what  Our  Lord  did  not 
grant,  because  there  were  others,  bound  by  the  duties  of  kindred, 
to  take  care  of  him. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Whatever  we  give  our  parents  out  of  piety 
is  referred  by  us  to  God;  just  as  other  works  of  mercy  which 
we  perform  with  regard  to  any  of  our  neighbours  are  offered 
to  God,  according  to  Matth.  xxv.  40:  As  long  as  you  did  it 
to  one  of  .  .  .  My  least  .  .  .  you  did  it  to  Me.  Accordingly, 
if  our  carnal  parents  stand  in  need  of  our  assistance,  so 
that  they  have  no  other  means  of  support,  provided  they 
incite  us  to  nothing  against  God,  we  must  not  abandon  them 
for  the  sake  of  religion.  But  if  we  cannot  devote  ourselves 
to  their  service  without  sin,  or  if  they  can  be  supported 
without  our  assistance,  it  is  lawful  to  forgo  their  service, 
so  as  to  give  more  time  to  religion. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  We  must  speak  differently  of  one  who  is  yet 
in  the  world,  and  of  one  who  has  made  his  profession  in 


9  PIETY  Q.101.ART.4 

religion.  For  he  that  is  in  the  world,  if  he  has  parents 
unable  to  find  support  without  him,  he  must  not  leave  them 
and  enter  religion,  because  he  would  be  breaking  the  com- 
mandment prescribing  the  honouring  of  parents.  Some  say, 
however,  that  even  then  he  might  abandon  them,  and  leave 
them  in  God's  care.  But  this,  considered  aright,  would  be 
to  tempt  God :  since,  while  having  human  means  at  hand,  he 
would  be  exposing  his  parents  to  danger,  in  the  hope  of  God's 
assistance.  On  the  other  hand,  if  the  parents  can  find 
means  of  livelihood  without  him,  it  is  lawful  for  him  to 
abandon  them  and  enter  religion,  because  children  are  not 
bound  to  support  their  parents  except  in  cases  of  necessity, 
as  stated  above.  He  that  has  already  made  his  profession 
in  religion  is  deemed  to  be  already  dead  to  the  world: 
wherefore  he  ought  not,  under  pretext  of  supporting  his 
parents,  to  leave  the  cloister  where  he  is  buried  with  Christ, 
and  busy  himself  once  more  with  worldly  affairs.  Neverthe- 
less he  is  bound,  saving  his  obedience  to  his  superiors,  and 
his  religious  state  withal,  to  make  pious  efforts  for  his 
parents'  support. 


QUESTION  CII. 

OF  OBSERVANCE,  CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF,  AND  OF  ITS 

PARTS. 

(In  Three  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  observance  and  its  parts,  the  con- 
siderations of  which  will  manifest  the  contrary  vices. 

Under  the  head  of  observance  there  are  three  points  of 
inquiry:  (i)  Whether  observance  is  a  special  virtue,  distinct 
from  other  virtues  ?  (2)  What  does  observance  offer  ? 
(3)  Of  its  comparison  with  piety. 

First  Article. 

whether  observance  is  a  special  virtue,  distinct  from 

other  virtues  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  observance  is  not  a  special 
virtue,  distinct  from  other  virtues.  For  virtues  are  dis- 
tinguished by  their  objects.  But  the  object  of  observance 
is  not  distinct  from  the  object  of  piety:  for  Tully  says  (Dc 
Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  it  is  by  observance  that  we  pay  worship  and 
honour  to  those  who  excel  in  some  kind  of  dignity.  But 
worship  and  honour  are  paid  also  by  piety  to  our  parents, 
who  excel  in  dignity.  Therefore  observance  is  not  a  distinct 
virtue  from  piety. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Just  as  honour  and  worship  are  due  to 
those  that  are  in  a  position  of  dignity,  so  also  are  they  due 
to  those  who  excel  in  science  and  virtue.  But  there  is  no 
special  virtue  whereby  we  pay  honour  and  worship 
to  those  who  excel  in  science  and  virtue.  Therefore  ob- 
servance, whereby  we  pay  worship  and  honour  to  those  who 

10 


ii  OBSERVANCE  Q.  102.  Art.  1 

excel  in  dignity,  is  not  a  special  virtue  distinct  from  other 
virtues. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  We  have  many  duties  towards  those 
who  are  in  a  position  of  dignity,  the  fulfilment  of  which  is 
required  by  law,  according  to  Rom.  xiii.  7,  Render  .  .  .  to 
all  men  their  dues:  tribute  to  whom  tribute  is  due,  etc.  Now  the 
fulfilment  of  the  requirements  of  the  law  belongs  to  legal 
justice,  or  even  to  special  justice.  Therefore  observance  is 
not  by  itself  a  special  virtue  distinct  from  other  virtues. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  (loc.  cit.)  reckons  observance  along 
with  the  other  parts  of  justice,  which  are  special  virtues. 

I  answer  that,  As  explained  above  (QQ.  CI.,  AA.  1,  3: 
LXXX.),  according  to  the  various  excellences  of  those  persons 
to  whom  something  is  due,  there  must  needs  be  a  correspond- 
ing distinction  of  virtues  in  a  descending  order.  Now  just 
as  a  carnal  father  partakes  of  the  character  of  principle 
in  a  particular  way,  which  character  is  found  in  God  in  a 
universal  way,  so  too  a  person  who,  in  some  way,  exercises 
providence  in  one  respect,  partakes  of  the  character  of  father 
in  a  p  articular  way,  since  a  father  is  the  principle  of  generation, 
of  education,  of  learning  and  of  whatever  pertains  to  the  per- 
fection of  human  life:  while  a  person  who  is  in  a  position 
of  dignity  is  as  a  principle  of  government  with  regard  to 
certain  things:  for  instance,  the  governor  of  a  state  in  civil 
matters,  the  commander  of  an  army  in  matters  of  warfare, 
a  professor  in  matters  of  learning,  and  so  forth.  Hence  it  is 
that  all  such  persons  are  designated  as  fathers,  on  account 
of  their  being  charged  with  like  cares:  thus  the  servants 
of  Naaman  said  to  him  (4  Kings  v.  13) :  Father,  if  the  prophet 
had  bid  thee  do  some  great  thing,  etc. 

Therefore,  just  as,  in  a  manner,  beneath  religion,  whereby 
worship  is  given  to  God,  we  find  piety,  whereby  we  worship 
our  parents,  so  under  piety  we  find  observance,  whereby 
worship  and  honour  are  paid  to  persons  in  positions  of 
dignity. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CI.,  A.  3,  ad  2),  religion 
goes  by  the  name  of  piety  by  way  of  supereminence,  although 
piety  properly  so  called  is  distinct  from  religion :  and  in  the 


Q.  102.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  12 

same  way  piety  can  be  called  observance  by  way  of  excel- 
lence, although  observance  properly  speaking  is  distinct 
from  piety. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  By  the  very  fact  of  being  in  a  position  of 
dignity  a  man  not  only  excels  as  regards  his  position,  but 
also  has  a  certain  power  of  governing  subjects,  wherefore 
it  is  fitting  that  he  should  be  considered  as  a  principle  inas- 
much as  he  is  the  governor  of  others.  On  the  other  hand, 
the  fact  that  a  man  has  perfection  of  science  and  virtue  does 
not  give  him  the  character  of  a  principle  in  relation  to  others, 
but  merely  a  certain  excellence  in  himself.  Wherefore  a 
special  virtue  is  appointed  for  the  payment  of  worship  and 
honour  to  persons  in  positions  of  dignity.  Yet,  forasmuch 
as  science,  virtue  and  all  like  things  render  a  man  fit  for 
positions  of  dignity,  the  respect  which  is  paid  to  anyone 
on  account  of  any  excellence  whatever  belongs  to  the  same 
virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  It  belongs  to  special  justice,  properly  speak- 
ing, to  pay  the  equivalent  to  those  to  whom  we  owe  any- 
thing. Now  this  cannot  be  done  to  the  virtuous,  and  to 
those  who  make  good  use  of  their  position  of  dignity,  as 
neither  can  it  be  done  to  God,  nor  to  our  parents.  Conse- 
quently these  matters  belong  to  an  annexed  virtue,  and  not 
to  special  justice,  which  is  a  principal  virtue. 

Legal  justice  extends  to  the  acts  of  all  the  virtues,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  LVIIL,  A.  6). 

Second  Article. 

whether  it  belongs   to  observance  to   pay  worship 
and   honour  to  those  who  are  in   positions   of 

DIGNITY  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  it  does  not  belong  to  observance 
to  pay  worship  and  honour  to  persons  in  positions  of  dignity. 
For  according  to  Augustine  (De  Civ.  Dei  x.),  we  are  said  to 
worship  those  persons  whom  we  hold  in  honour,  so  that 
worship  and  honour  would  seem  to  be  the  same.     Therefore 


13  OBSERVANCE  Q.  102.  Art.  2 

it  is  unfitting  to  define  observance  as  paying  worship  and 
honour  to  persons  in  positions  of  dignity. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  It  belongs  to  justice  that  we  pay  what 
we  owe :  wherefore  this  belongs  to  observance  also,  since  it 
is  a  part  of  justice.  Now  we  do  not  owe  worship  and  honour 
to  all  persons  in  positions  of  dignity,  but  only  to  those  who 
are  placed  over  us.  Therefore  observance  is  unfittingly 
defined  as  giving  worship  and  honour  to  all. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Not  only  do  we  owe  honour  to  persons 
of  dignity  who  are  placed  over  us;  we  owe  them  also  fear 
and  a  certain  payment  of  remuneration,  according  to 
Rom.  xiii.  7,  Render  .  .  .to  all  men  their  dues;  tribute  to  whom 
tribute  is  due  ;  custom  to  whom  custom ;  fear  to  whom  fear  ; 
honour  to  whom  honour.  Moreover,  we  owe  them  reverence 
and  subjection,  according  to  Heb.  xiii.  17,  Obey  your  prelates, 
and  be  subject  to  them.  Therefore  observance  is  not  fittingly 
defined  as  paying  worship  and  honour. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  says  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  it  is  by 
observance  that  we  pay  worship  and  honour  to  those  who  excel 
in  some  kind  of  dignity. 

I  answer  that,  It  belongs  to  persons  in  positions  of  dignit}' 
to  govern  subjects.  Now  to  govern  is  to  move  certain  ones 
to  their  due  end :  thus  a  sailor  governs  his  ship  by  steering 
it  to  port.  But  every  mover  has  a  certain  excellence  and 
power  over  that  which  is  moved.  Wherefore,  a  person  in  a 
position  of  dignity  is  an  object  of  twofold  consideration: 
first,  in  so  far  as  he  obtains  excellence  of  position,  together 
with  a  certain  power  over  subjects:  secondly,  as  regards  the 
exercise  of  his  government.  In  respect  of  his  excellence 
there  is  due  to  him  honour,  which  is  the  recognition  of  some 
kind  of  excellence;  and  in  respect  of  the  exercise  of  his 
government,  there  is  due  to  him  worship,  consisting  in 
rendering  him  service,  by  obeying  his  commands,  and  by 
repaying  him,  according  to  one's  faculty,  for  the  benefits  we 
receive  from  him. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Worship  includes  not  only  honour,  but  also 
whatever  other  suitable  actions  are  connected  with  the 
relations  between  man  and  man. 


Q.  102.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  14 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  stated  above  (Q.  LXXX.),  debt  is  two- 
fold. One  is  legal  debt,  to  pay  which  man  is  compelled  by 
law;  and  thus  man  owes  honour  and  worship  to  those  persons 
in  positions  of  dignity  who  are  placed  over  him.  The  other 
is  moral  debt,  which  is  due  by  reason  of  a  certain  honesty : 
it  is  in  this  way  that  we  owe  worship  and  honour  to  persons 
in  positions  of  dignity  even  though  we  be  not  their  subjects. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Honour  is  due  to  the  excellence  of  persons 
in  positions  of  dignity,  on  account  of  their  higher  rank :  while 
fear  is  due  to  them  on  account  of  their  power  to  use  compul- 
sion: and  to  the  exercise  of  their  government  there  is  due 
both  obedience,  whereby  subjects  are  moved  at  the  com- 
mand of  their  superiors,  and  tributes,  which  are  a  repay- 
ment of  their  labour. 

Third  Article, 
whether  observance  is  a  greater  virtue  than  piety? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  observance  is  a  greater  virtue 
than  piety.  For  the  prince  to  whom  worship  is  paid  by 
observance  is  compared  to  a  father  who  is  worshipped  by 
piety,  as  a  universal  to  a  particular  governor;  because  the 
household  which  a  father  governs  is  part  of  the  state  which 
is  governed  by  the  prince.  Now  a  universal  power  is  greater, 
and  inferiors  are  more  subject  thereto.  Therefore  obser 
vance  is  a  greater  virtue  than  piety. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Persons  in  positions  of  dignity  take  care 
of  the  common  good.  Now  our  kindred  pertain  to  the 
private  good,  which  we  ought  to  set  aside  for  the  common 
good :  wherefore  it  is  praiseworthy  to  expose  oneself  to  the 
danger  of  death  for  the  sake  of  the  common  good.  There 
fore  observance,  whereby  worship  is  paid  to  persons  in  posi- 
tions of  dignity,  is  a  greater  virtue  than  piety,  which  pays 
worship  to  one's  kindred. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Honour  and  reverence  are  due  to  the 
virtuous  in  the  first  place  after  God.  Now  honour  and 
reverence  are  paid  to  the  virtuous  by  the  virtue  of  obser- 


15  OBSERVANCE  Q.  102.  Art.  3 

vance,  as  stated  above  (A.  1,  ad  3).     Therefore  observance 
takes  the  first  place  after  religion. 

On  the  contrary,  The  precepts  of  the  Law  prescribe  acts 
of  virtue.  Now,  immediately  after  the  precepts  of  religion, 
which  belong  to  the  first  table,  follows  the  precept  of  honour- 
ing our  parents,  which  refers  to  piety.  Therefore  piety 
follows  immediately  after  religion  in  the  order  of  excellence. 

/  answer  that,  Something  may  be  paid  to  persons  in 
positions  of  dignity  in  two  ways.  First,  in  relation  to  the 
common  good,  as  when  one  serves  them  in  the  administration 
of  the  affairs  of  the  state.  This  no  longer  belongs  to 
observance,  but  to  piety,  which  pays  worship  not  only  to 
one's  father  but  also  to  one's  fatherland.  Secondly,  that 
which  is  paid  to  persons  in  positions  of  dignity  refers 
specially  to  their  personal  usefulness  or  renown,  and  this 
belongs  properly  to  observance,  as  distinct  from  piety. 
Therefore  in  comparing  observance  with  piety  we  must 
needs  take  into  consideration  the  different  relations  in  which 
other  persons  stand  to  ourselves,  which  relations  both 
virtues  regard.  Now  it  is  evident  that  the  persons  of  our 
parents  and  of  our  kindred  are  more  substantially  akin  to 
us  than  persons  in  positions  of  dignity,  since  birth  and 
education,  which  originate  in  the  father,  belong  more  to  one's 
substance  than  external  government,  the  principle  of  which 
is  seated  in  those  who  are  in  positions  of  dignity.  For  this 
reason  piety  takes  precedence  of  observance,  inasmuch 
as  it  pays  worship  to  persons  more  akin  to  us,  and  to  whom 
we  are  more  strictly  bound. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  prince  is  compared  to  the  father  as 
a  universal  to  a  particular  power,  as  regards  external 
government,  but  not  as  regards  the  father  being  a  principle 
of  generation :  for  in  this  way  the  father  should  be  compared 
with  the  divine  power  from  which  all  things  derive  their 
being. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  In  so  far  as  persons  in  positions  of  dignity 
are  related  to  the  common  good,  their  worship  does  not 
pertain  to  observance,  but  to  piety,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  rendering  of  honour  or  worship  should 


Q.  T02.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  16 

be  proportionate  to  the  person  to  whom  it  is  paid  not  only  as 
considered  in  himself,  but  also  as  compared  to  those  who 
pay  them.  Wherefore,  though  virtuous  persons,  considered 
in  themselves,  are  more  worthy  of  honour  than  the  persons 
of  one's  parents,  yet  children  are  under  a  greater  obligation, 
on  account  of  the  benefits  they  have  received  from  their 
parents  and  their  natural  kinship  with  them,  to  pay  worship 
and  honour  to  their  parents  than  to  virtuous  persons  who 
are  not  of  their  kindred. 


QUESTION  CIII. 

OF  DULIA. 
(In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  parts  of  observance.  We  shall 
consider  (i)  dulia  whereby  we  pay  honour  and  other  things 
pertaining  thereto  to  those  who  are  in  a  higher  position: 
(2)  obedience,  whereby  we  obey  their  commands. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry: 

(1)  Whether  honour  is  a  spiritual  or  a  corporal  thing  ? 

(2)  Whether  honour  is  due  to  those  only  who  are  in  a  higher 
position  ?  (3)  Whether  dulia,  which  pays  honour  and 
worship  to  those  who  are  above  us,  is  a  special  virtue, 
distinct  from  latria  ?  (4)  Whether  it  contains  several 
species  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  honour  denotes  something  corporal  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  honour  does  not  denote  some- 
thing corporal.  For  honour  is  showing  reverence  in  ac- 
knowledgement of  virtue,  as  may  be  gathered  from  the 
Philosopher  (Ethic,  i.  5).  Now  showing  reverence  is  some- 
thing spiritual,  since  to  revere  is  an  act  of  fear,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  LXXXI.,  A.  2,  ad  1).  Therefore  honour  is  some- 
thing spiritual. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  According  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  3), 
honour  is  the  reward  of  virtue.  Now,  since  virtue  consists 
chiefly  of  spiritual  things,  its  reward  is  not  something 
corporal,  for  the  reward  is  more  excellent  than  the  merit. 
Therefore  honour  does  not  consist  of  corporal  things. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Honour  is  distinct  from  praise,  as  also 
n.  ii.  4  17  2 


Q.  103.  Art.  i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  18 

from  glory.  Now  praise  and  glory  consist  of  external 
things.  Therefore  honour  consists  of  things  internal  and 
spiritual. 

On  the  contrary,  Jerome  in  his  exposition  of  1  Tim.  v.  3, 
Honour  widows  that  are  widows  indeed,  and  {verse  17),  let 
the  priests  that  rule  well  be  esteemed  worthy  of  double  honour 
etc.,  says  {Ep.  ad  Ageruch.):  Honour  here  stands  either  for 
almsgiving  or  for  remuneration.  Now  both  of  these  pertain 
to  spiritual  things.  Therefore  honour  consists  of  corporal 
things. 

/  answer  that,  Honour  denotes  a  witnessing  to  a  person's 
excellence.  Therefore  men  who  wish  to  be  honoured  seek 
a  witnessing  to  their  excellence,  according  to  the  Philosopher 
{Ethic,  i.  5,  viii.  8).  Now  witness  is  borne  either  before  God 
or  before  man.  Before  God,  Who  is  the  searcher  of  hearts, 
the  witness  of  one's  conscience  suffices;  wherefore  honour, 
so  far  as  God  is  concerned,  may  consist  of  the  mere  internal 
movement  of  the  heart,  for  instance  when  a  man  acknow- 
ledges either  God's  excellence  or  another  man's  excellence 
before  God.  But,  as  regards  men,  one  cannot  bear  witness, 
save  by  means  of  signs,  either  by  wrords,  as  when  one  pro- 
claims another's  excellence  by  word  of  mouth,  or  by  deeds, 
for  instance  by  bowing,  saluting,  and  so  forth,  or  by  external 
things,  as  by  offering  gifts,  erecting  statues,  and  the  like. 
Accordingly  honour  consists  of  signs,  external  and  corporal. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Reverence  is  not  the  same  as  honour:  but 
on  the  one  hand  it  is  the  primary  motive  for  showing  honour, 
in  so  far  as  one  man  honours  another  out  of  the  reverence  he 
has  for  him;  and  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  the  end  of  honour, 
in  so  far  as  a  person  is  honoured  in  order  that  he  may  be  held 
in  reverence  by  others. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  According  to  the  Philosopher  {ibid.), 
honour  is  not  a  sufficient  reward  of  virtue :  yet  nothing  in 
human  and  corporal  things  can  be  greater  than  honour, 
since  these  corporal  things  themselves  are  employed  as  signs 
in  acknowledgement  of  excelling  virtue.  It  is,  however, 
due  to  the  good  and  the  beautiful,  that  they  may  be  made 
known,  according  to  Matth.  v.  15,  Neither  do  men  light  a 


ig  DULIA  Q.  103.  Art.  i 

candle,  and  put  it  under  a  bushel,  but  upon  a  candlestick,  that 
it  may  shine  to  all  that  are  in  the  house.  In  this  sense  honour 
is  said  to  be  the  reward  of  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Praise  is  distinguished  from  honour  in 
two  ways.  First,  because  praise  consists  only  of  verbal 
signs,  whereas  honour  consists  of  any  external  signs,  so  that 
praise  is  included  in  honour.  Secondly,  because  by  paying 
honour  to  a  person  we  bear  witness  to  a  person's  excelling 
goodness  absolutely,  whereas  by  praising  him  we  bear 
witness  to  his  goodness  in  reference  to  an  end:  thus  we 
praise  one  that  works  well  for  an  end.  On  the  other  hand, 
honour  is  given  even  to  the  best,  which  is  not  referred  to 
an  end,  but  has  already  arrived  at  the  end,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  {Ethic,  i.  5). 

Glory  is  the  effect  of  honour  and  praise,  since  the  result 
of  our  bearing  witness  to  a  person's  goodness  is  that  his 
goodness  becomes  clear  to  the  knowledge  of  many.  The 
word  glory  signifies  this,  for  glory  is  the  same  as  KXvpla, 
wherefore  a  gloss  of  Augustine  on  Rom.  xvi.  27  observes  that 
glory  is  clear  knowledge  together  with  praise. 

Second  Article, 
whether  honour  is  properly  due  to  those  who   are 

ABOVE   US  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  honour  is  not  properly  due  to 
those  who  are  above  us.  For  an  angel  is  above  any  human 
wayfarer,  according  to  Matth.  xi.  n,  He  that  is  lesser  in  the 
kingdom  of  heaven  is  greater  than  John  the  Baptist.  Yet 
an  angel  forbade  John  when  the  latter  wished  to  honour  him 
(Apoc.  xxii.  10).  Therefore  honour  is  not  due  to  those  who 
are  above  us. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Honour  is  due  to  a  person  in  acknowledge- 
ment of  his  virtue,  as  stated  above  (A.  1:  Q.  LXIIL,  A.  3). 
But  sometimes  those  who  are  above  us  are  not  virtuous. 
Therefore  honour  is  not  due  to  them,  as  neither  is  it  due  to  the 
demons,  who  nevertheless  are  above  us  in  the  order  of  nature. 


Q.  103.  Art  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  20 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  xii.  10) :  With 
honour  preventing  one  another,  and  we  read  (1  Pet.  ii.  17) : 
Honour  all  men.  But  this  would  not  be  so  if  honour  were 
due  to  those  alone  who  are  above  us.  Therefore  honour  is  not 
due  properly  to  those  who  are  above  us. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  It  is  written  (Tob  i.  16)  that  Tobias  had 
ten  talents  of  silver  of  that  with  which  he  had  been  honoured  by 
the  king:  and  we  read  (Esther  vi.  n)  that  Assuerus  honoured 
Mardochaeus,  and  ordered  it  to  be  proclaimed  in  his  presence : 
This  honour  is  he  worthy  of  whom  the  king  hath  a  mind  to 
honour.  Therefore  honour  is  paid  to  those  also  who  are 
beneath  us,  and  it  seems,  in  consequence,  that  honour  is 
not  due  properly  to  those  who  are  above  us. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  sa}-s  [Ethic,  i.  12)  that 
honour  is  due  to  the  best. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  1),  honour  is  nothing 
but  an  acknowledgement  of  a  person's  excelling  goodness. 
Now  a  person's  excellence  may  be  considered,  not  only  in 
relation  to  those  who  honour  him,  in  the  point  of  his  being 
more  excellent  than  they,  but  also  in  itself,  or  in  relation  to 
other  persons,  and  in  this  way  honour  is  always  due  to  a 
person,  on  account  of  some  excellence  or  superiority.  For  the 
person  honoured  has  no  need  to  be  more  excellent  than  those 
who  honour  him ;  it  may  suffice  for  him  to  be  more  excellent 
than  some  others,  or  again  he  may  be  more  excellent  than 
those  who  honour  him  in  some  respect  and  not  simply. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  angel  forbade  John  to  pay  him,  not 
any  kind  of  honour,  but  the  honour  of  adoration  and 
latria,  which  is  due  to  God.  Or  again,  he  forbade  him  to 
pay  the  honour  of  dulia,  in  order  to  indicate  the  dignity  of 
John  himself,  for  which  Christ  equalled  him  to  the  angels 
according  to  the  hope  of  glory  of  the  children  of  God:  wherefore 
he  refused  to  be  honoured  by  him  as  though  he  were  superior 
to  him. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  A  wicked  superior  is  honoured  for  the 
excellence,  not  of  his  virtue  but  of  his  dignity,  as  being 
God's  minister,  and  because  the  honour  paid  to  him  is  paid 
to  the  whole  community  over  which  he  presides.     As  for 


21  DULIA  Q.  103.  Art.  3 

the  demons,  they  are  wicked  beyond  recall,  and  should  be 
looked  upon  as  enemies,  rather  than  treated  with  honour. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  every  man  is  to  be  found  something  that 
makes  it  possible  to  deem  him  better  than  ourselves,  accord- 
ing to  Philip,  ii.  3,  In  humility,  let  each  esteem  others  better 
than  themselves,  and  thus,  too,  we  should  all  be  on  the  alert 
to  do  honour  to  one  another. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Private  individuals  are  sometimes  honoured 
by  kings,  not  that  they  are  above  them  in  the  order  of  dignity 
but  on  account  of  some  excellence  of  their  virtue :  and  in  this 
way  Tobias  and  Mardochaeus  were  honoured  by  kings. 

Third.  Article, 
whether  dulia  is  a  special  virtue  distinct  from 

LATRIA  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  dulia  is  not  a  special  virtue 
distinct  from  latria.  For  a  gloss  on  Ps.  vii.  1,  0  Lord  my  God, 
in  Thee  have  I  put  my  trust,  says :  Lord  of  all  by  His  power,  to 
Whom  dulia  is  due  ;  God  by  creation,  to  Whom  we  owe  latria. 
Now  the  virtue  directed  to  God  as  Lord  is  not  distinct  from 
that  which  is  directed  to  Him  as  God.  Therefore  dulia  is 
not  a  distinct  virtue  from  latria. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  According  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  viii.  8), 
to  be  loved  is  like  being  honoured.  Now  the  charity  with  which 
we  love  God  is  the  same  as  that  whereby  we  love  our  neigh- 
bour. Therefore  dulia  whereby  we  honour  our  neighbour 
is  not  a  distinct  virtue  from  latria  with  which  we  honour  God. 

Obj .  3.  Further,  The  movement  whereby  one  is  moved 
towards  an  image  is  the  same  as  the  movement  whereby 
one  is  moved  towards  the  thing  represented  by  the  image. 
Now  by  dulia  we  honour  a  man  as  being  made  to  the  image 
of  God.  For  it  is  written  of  the  wicked  (Wis.  ii.  22,  23)  that 
they  esteemed  not  the  honour  of  holy  souls,  for  God  created  man 
incorruptible,  and  to  the  image  of  His  own  likeness  He  made  him. 
Therefore  dulia  is  not  a  distinct  virtue  from  latria  whereby 
God  is  honoured. 


Q.  103.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  22 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Dc  Civ.  Dei  x.)  that  the 
homage  due  to  man,  of  which  the  Apostle  spoke  when  he  com- 
manded servants  to  obey  their  masters,  and  which  in  Greek  is 
called  dulia,  is  distinct  Jrom  latria,  which  denotes  the  homage 
that  consists  in  the  worship  of  God. 

I  answer  that,  According  to  what  has  been  stated  above 
(0.  CI.,  A.  3),  where  there  are  different  aspects  of  that  which 
is  due,  there  must  needs  be  different  virtues  to  render  those 
dues.  Now  servitude  is  due  to  God  and  to  man  under  different 
aspects:  even  as  lordship  is  competent  to  God  and  to  man 
under  different  aspects.  For  God  has  absolute  and  paramount 
lordship  over  the  creature  wholly  and  singly,  which  is  entirely 
subject  to  His  power:  whereas  man  partakes  of  a  certain 
likeness  to  the  divine  lordship,  forasmuch  as  he  exercises 
a  particular  power  over  some  man  or  creature.  Wherefore 
dulia,  which  pays  due  service  to  a  human  lord,  is  a  distinct 
virtue  from  latria,  which  pays  due  service  to  the  lordship  of 
God.  It  is,  moreover,  a  species  of  observance,  because  by 
observance  we  honour  all  those  who  excel  in  dignity,  while 
dulia  properly  speaking  is  the  reverence  of  servants  for  their 
master,  dulia  being  the  Greek  for  servitude. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Just  as  religion  is  called  piety  by  way  of 
excellence,  inasmuch  as  God  is  our  Father  by  way  of  ex- 
cellence, so  again  latria  is  called  dulia  by  way  of  excellence, 
inasmuch  as  God  is  our  Lord  by  way  of  excellence.  Now 
the  creature  does  not  partake  of  the  power  to  create  by 
reason  of  which  latria  is  due  to  God :  and  so  this  gloss  drew 
a  distinction,  by  ascribing  latria  to  God  in  respect  of 
creation,  which  is  not  communicated  to  a  creature,  but 
dulia  in  respect  of  lordship,  which  is  communicated  to  a 
creature. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  reason  why  we  love  our  neighbour  is 
God,  since  that  which  we  love  in  our  neighbour  through 
charity  is  God  alone.  Wherefore  the  charity  with  which 
we  love  God  is  the  same  as  that  with  which  we  love  our 
neighbour.  Yet  there  are  other  friendships  distinct  from 
charity,  in  respect  of  the  other  reasons  for  which  a  man  is 
loved.     In  like  manner,  since  there  is  one  reason  for  serving 


23  DULIA  Q.  103.  Art.  4 

God  and  another  for  serving  man,  and  for  honouring  the  one 
or  the  other,  latria  and  dulia  are  not  the  same  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Movement  towards  an  image  as  such  is 
referred  to  the  thing  represented  by  the  image :  yet  not  every 
movement  towards  an  image  is  referred  to  the  image  as  such, 
and  consequently  sometimes  the  movement  to  the  image 
differs  specifically  from  the  movement  to  the  thing.  Accor- 
dingly we  must  reply  that  the  honour  or  subjection  of  dulia 
regards  some  dignity  of  a  man  absolutely.  For  though,  in 
respect  of  that  dignity,  man  is  made  to  the  image  or  likeness 
of  God,  yet  in  showing  reverence  to  a  person,  one  does  not 
always  refer  this  to  God  actually. 

Or  we  may  reply  that  the  movement  towards  an  image 
is,  after  a  fashion,  towards  the  thing,  yet  the  movement 
towards  the  thing  need  not  be  towards  its  image.  Where- 
fore reverence  paid  to  a  person  as  the  image  of  God  redounds 
somewhat  to  God:  and  yet  this  differs  from  the  reverence 
that  is  paid  to  God  Himself,  for  this  in  no  way  refers  to  His 
image. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  dulia  has  various  species  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  dulia  has  various  species.  For 
by  dulia  we  show  honour  to  our  neighbour.  Now  different 
neighbours  are  honoured  under  different  aspects,  for  instance 
king,  father  and  master,  as  the  Philosopher  states  (Ethic,  ix.  2). 
Since  this  difference  of  aspect  in  the  object  differentiates 
the  species  of  virtue,  it  seems  that  dulia  is  divided  into 
specifically  different  virtues. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  mean  differs  specifically  from  the 
extremes,  as  pale  differs  from  white  and  black.  No\v  hyper- 
dulia  is  apparently  a  mean  between  latria  and  dulia:  for 
it  is  shown  towards  creatures  having  a  special  affinity  to 
God,  for  instance  to  the  Blessed  Virgin  as  being  the  mother 
of  God.  Therefore  it  seems  that  there  are  different  species 
of  dulia,  one  being  simply  dulia,  the  other  hyperdulia. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Just  as  in  the  rational  creature  we  find 


Q.  103.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  24 

the  image  of  God,  for  which  reason  it  is  honoured,  so  too  in 
the  irrational  creature  we  find  the  trace  of  God.  Now  the 
aspect  of  likeness  denoted  by  an  image  differs  from  the 
aspect  conveyed  by  a  trace.  Therefore  we  must  distinguish 
a  corresponding  difference  of  dulia:  and  all  the  more  since 
honour  is  shown  to  certain  irrational  creatures,  as,  for  in- 
stance, to  the  wood  of  the  Holy  Cross. 

On  the  contrary,  Dulia  is  condivided  with  latria.  But  latria 
is  not  divided  into  different  species.  Neither  therefore  is 
dulia. 

/  answer  that,  Dulia  may  be  taken  in  two  ways.  In  one 
way  it  may  be  taken  in  a  wide  sense  as  denoting  reverence 
paid  to  anyone  on  account  of  any  kind  of  excellence,  and 
thus  it  comprises  piety  and  observance,  and  any  similar 
virtue  whereby  reverence  is  shown  towards  a  man.  Taken 
in  this  sense  it  will  have  parts  differing  specifically  from  one 
another.  In  another  way  it  may  be  taken  in  a  strict  sense 
as  denoting  the  reverence  of  a  servant  for  his  lord,  for  dulia 
signifies  servitude,  as  stated  above  (A.  3).  Taken  in  this 
sense  it  is  not  divided  into  different  species,  but  is  one  of  the 
species  of  observance,  mentioned  by  Tully  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.), 
for  the  reason  that  a  servant  reveres  his  lord  under  one 
aspect,  a  soldier  his  commanding  officer  under  another,  the 
disciple  his  master  under  another,  and  so  on  in  similar  cases. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  argument  takes  dulia  in  a  wide  sense. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Hyper  dulia  is  the  highest  species  of  dulia 
taken  in  a  wide  sense,  since  the  greatest  reverence  is  that 
which  is  due  to  a  man  by  reason  of  his  having  an  affinity  to 
God. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Man  owes  neither  subjection  nor  honour  to 
an  irrational  creature  considered  in  itself,  indeed  all  such 
creatures  are  naturally  subject  to  man.  As  to  the  Cross 
of  Christ,  the  honour  we  pay  to  it  is  the  same  as  that 
winch  we  pay  to  Christ,  just  as  the  king's  robe  receives  the 
same  honour  as  the  king  himself,  according  to  Damascene 
(De  Fide  Orthod.  iv.). 


QUESTION   CIV. 

OF  OBEDIENCE. 
(In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  obedience,  under  which  head  there 
are  six  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  one  man  is  bound  to 
obey  another  ?  (2)  Whether  obedience  is  a  special  virtue  ? 
(3)  Of  its  comparison  with  other  virtues :  (4)  Whether  God 
must  be  obeyed  in  all  things  ?  (5)  Whether  subjects  are 
bound  to  obey  their  superiors  in  all  things  ?  (6)  Whether 
the  faithful  are  bound  to  obey  the  secular  power  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  one  man  is  bound  to  obey  another  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  one  man  is  not  bound  to  obey 
another.  For  nothing  should  be  done  contrary  to  the  divine 
ordinance.  Now  God  has  so  ordered  that  man  is  ruled  by 
his  own  counsel,  according  to  Ecclus.  xv.  14,  God  made  man 
from  the  beginning,  and  left  him  in  the  hand  of  his  own  counsel. 
Therefore  one  man  is  not  bound  to  obey  another. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  If  one  man  were  bound  to  obey  another, 
he  would  have  to  look  upon  the  will  of  the  person  command- 
ing him,  as  being  his  rule  of  conduct.  Now  God's  will  alone, 
which  is  always  right,  is  a  rule  of  human  conduct.  There- 
fore man  is  bound  to  obey  none  but  God. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  more  gratuitous  the  service  the  more 
is  it  acceptable.  Now  what  a  man  does  out  of  duty  is  not 
gratuitous.  Therefore  if  a  man  were  bound  in  duty  to  obey 
others  in  doing  good  deeds,  for  this  very  reason  his  good 
deeds  would  be  rendered  less  acceptable  through  being  done 

25 


Q.io4.Art.i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  26 

out  of  obedience.  Therefore  one  man  is  not  bound  to  obey 
another. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  prescribed  (Heb.  xiii.  17) :  Obey 
your  prelates  and  be  subject  to  them. 

I  answer  that,  Just  as  the  actions  of  natural  things  proceed 
from  natural  powers,  so  do  human  actions  proceed  from  the 
human  will.  In  natural  things  it  behoved  the  higher  to 
move  the  lower  to  their  actions  by  the  excellence  of  the 
natural  power  bestowed  on  them  by  God :  and  so  in  human 
affairs  also  the  higher  must  move  the  lower  by  their  will  in 
virtue  of  a  divinely  established  authority.  Now  to  move 
by  reason  and  will  is  to  command.  Wherefore  just  as  in 
virtue  of  the  divinely  established  natural  order  the  lower 
natural  things  need  to  be  subject  to  the  movement  of  the 
higher,  so  too  in  human  affairs,  in  virtue  of  the  order  of 
natural  and  divine  law,  inferiors  are  bound  to  obey  their 
superiors. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  God  left  man  in  the  hand  of  his  own  counsel, 
not  as  though  it  were  lawful  to  him  to  do  whatever  he  will, 
but  because,  unlike  irrational  creatures,  he  is  not  compelled 
by  natural  necessity  to  do  what  he  ought  to  do,  but  is  left 
the  free  choice  proceeding  from  his  own  counsel.  And  just 
as  he  has  to  proceed  on  his  own  counsel  in  doing  other  things, 
so  too  has  he  in  the  point  of  obeying  his  superiors.  For 
Gregory  says  (Moral,  xxxv.),  When  we  humbly  give  way  to 
another's  voice,  we  overcome  ourselves  in  our  own  hearts. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  will  of  God  is  the  first  rule  whereby 
all  rational  wills  are  regulated:  and  to  this  rule  one  will 
approaches  more  than  another,  according  to  a  divinely 
appointed  order.  Hence  the  will  of  the  one  man  who  issues 
a  command  may  be  as  a  second  rule  to  the  will  of  this  other 
man  who  obeys  him. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  A  thing  may  be  deemed  gratuitous  in  two 
ways.  In  one  way  on  the  part  of  the  deed  itself,  because, 
to  wit,  one  is  not  bound  to  do  it ;  in  another  way,  on  the  part 
of  the  doer,  because  he  does  it  of  his  own  free  will.  Now  a 
deed  is  rendered  virtuous,  praiseworthy  and  meritorious, 
chiefly  according  as  it  proceeds  from  the  will.     Wherefore 


27  OBEDIENCE  Q.  104.  Art.  2 

although  obedience  be  a  duty,  if  one  obey  with  a  prompt 
will,  one's  merit  is  not  for  that  reason  diminished,  especially 
before  God,  Who  sees  not  only  the  outward  deed,  but  also 
the  inward  will. 

Second  Article. 

whether  obedience  is  a  special  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  obedience  is  not  a  special 
virtue.  For  disobedience  is  contrary  to  obedience.  But 
disobedience  is  a  general  sin,  because  Ambrose  says  (De 
Par  ad.  viii.)  that  sin  is  to  disobey  the  divine  law.  Therefore 
obedience  is  not  a  special  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Every  special  virtue  is  either  theological 
or  moral.  But  obedience  is  not  a  theological  virtue,  since 
it  is  not  comprised  under  faith,  hope  or  charity.  Nor  is  it  a 
moral  virtue,  since  it  does  not  hold  the  mean  between  excess 
and  deficiency,  for  the  more  obedient  one  is  the  more  is  one 
praised.     Therefore  obedience  is  not  a  special  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Gregory  says  {Moral,  xxxv.)  that  obe- 
dience is  the  more  meritorious  and  praiseworthy,  the  less  it 
holds  its  own.  But  every  special  virtue  is  the  more  to  be 
praised  the  more  it  holds  its  own,  since  virtue  requires  a 
man  to  exercise  his  will  and  choice,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  ii.  4. 
Therefore  obedience  is  not  a  special  virtue. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Virtues  differ  in  species  according  to 
their  objects.  Now  the  object  of  obedience  would  seem  to 
be  the  command  of  a  superior,  of  which,  apparently,  there 
are  as  many  kinds  as  there  are  degrees  of  superiority.  There- 
fore obedience  is  a  general  virtue,  comprising  many  special 
virtues. 

On  the  contrary,  Obedience  is  reckoned  by  some  to  be  a 
part  of  justice,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXX.). 

I  answer  that,  A  special  virtue  is  assigned  to  all  good 
deeds  that  have  a  special  reason  of  praise:  for  it  belongs 
properly  to  virtue  to  render  a  deed  good.  Now  obedience 
to  a  superior  is  due  in  accordance  with  the  divinely  estab- 
lished order  of  things,  as  shown  above  (A.  1),  and  therefore 


Q.  104.  Art.  2  THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  28 

it  is  a  good,  since  good  consists  in  mode,  species  and  order, 
as  Augustine  states  (De  Natura  Boni  iii.).*  Again,  this  act 
has  a  special  aspect  of  praise  worthiness  by  reason  of  its 
object.  For  while  subjects  have  many  obligations  towards 
their  superiors,  this  one,  that  they  are  bound  to  obey  their 
commands,  stands  out  as  special  among  the  rest.  Where- 
fore obedience  is  a  special  virtue,  and  its  specific  object  is  a 
command  tacit  or  express,  because  the  superior's  will, 
however  it  become  known,  is  a  tacit  precept,  and  a  man's 
obedience  seems  to  be  all  the  more  prompt,  forasmuch  as 
by  obeying  he  forestalls  the  express  command  as  soon  as  he 
understands  his  superior's  will. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Nothing  prevents  the  one  same  material 
object  from  admitting  two  special  aspects  to  which  two 
special  virtues  correspond:  thus  a  soldier,  by  defending 
his  king's  fortress,  fulfils  both  an  act  of  fortitude,  by  facing 
the  danger  of  death  for  a  good  end,  and  an  act  of  justice, 
by  rendering  due  service  to  his  lord.  Accordingly  the 
aspect  of  precept,  which  obedience  considers,  occurs  in  acts 
of  all  virtues,  but  not  in  all  acts  of  virtue,  since  not  all  acts 
of  virtue  are  a  matter  of  precept,  as  stated  above  (I.-II., 
Q.  XCVL,  A.  3).  Moreover,  certain  things  are  sometimes  a 
matter  of  precept,  and  pertain  to  no  other  virtue,  such  things 
for  instance  as  are  not  evil  except  because  they  are  forbidden. 
Wherefore,  if  obedience  be  taken  in  its  proper  sense,  as 
considering  formally  and  intention  ally  the  aspect  of  precept, 
it  will  be  a  special  virtue,  and  disobedience  a  special  sin: 
because  in  this  way  it  is  requisite  for  obedience  that  one 
perform  an  act  of  justice  or  of  some  other  virtue  with  the 
intention  of  fulfilling  a  precept ;  and  for  disobedience  that 
one  treat  the  precept  with  actual  contempt.  On  the  other 
hand,  if  obedience  be  taken  in  a  wide  sense  for  the  perform- 
ance of  any  action  that  may  be  a  matter  of  precept,  and 
disobedience  for  the  omission  of  that  action  through  any 
intention  whatever,  then  obedience  will  be  a  general  virtue, 
and  disobedience  a  general  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Obedience  is  not   a  theological  virtue,  for 

*  Cf.  P.  i  Q.  V.,  A.  5. 


20,  OBEDIENCE  Q.  104.  Art  2 

its  direct  object  is  not  God,  but  the  precept  of  any  superior, 
whether  expressed  or  inferred,  namely,  a  simple  word  of  the 
superior,  indicating  his  will,  and  which  the  obedient  subject 
obeys  promptly,  according  to  Tit.  hi.  1,  Admonish  them  to  be 
subject  to  princes,  and  to  obey  at  a  word,  etc. 

It  is,  however,  a  moral  virtue,  since  it  is  a  part  of  justice, 
and  it  observes  the  mean  between  excess  and  deficiency. 
Excess  thereof  is  measured  in  respect,  not  of  quantity,  but 
of  other  circumstances,  in  so  far  as  a  man  obeys  either 
whom  he  ought  not,  or  in  matters  wherein  he  ought  not  to 
obey,  as  we  have  stated  above  regarding  religion  (Q.  XCII., 
A.  2).  We  may  also  reply  that  as  in  justice,  excess  is  in 
the  person  who  retains  another's  property,  and  deficiency 
in  the  person  who  does  not  receive  his  due,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  (Ethic,  v.  4),  so  too  obedience  observes  the  mean 
between  excess  on  the  part  of  him  who  fails  to  pay  due  obe- 
dience to  his  superior,  since  he  exceeds  in  fulfilling  his  own 
will,  and  deficiency  on  the  part  of  the  superior,  who  does 
not  receive  obedience.  Wherefore  in  this  way  obedience 
will  be  a  mean  between  two  forms  of  wickedness,  as  was 
stated  above  concerning  justice  (Q.  LVIII.,  A.  10). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Obedience,  like  every  virtue,  requires  the 
will  to  be  prompt  towards  its  proper  object,  but  not  towards 
that  which  is  repugnant  to  it.  Now  the  proper  object  of 
obedience  is  a  precept,  and  this  proceeds  from  another's  will. 
Wherefore  obedience  makes  a  man's  will  prompt  in  fulfilling 
the  will  of  another,  the  maker,  namely,  of  the  precept.  If 
that  which  is  prescribed  to  him  is  willed  by  him  for  its 
own  sake  apart  from  its  being  prescribed,  as  happens  in 
agreeable  matters,  he  tends  towards  it  at  once  by  his  own 
will,  and  seems  to  comply,  not  on  account  of  the  precept,  but 
on  account  of  his  own  will.  But  if  that  which  is  prescribed 
is  nowise  willed  for  its  own  sake,  but,  considered  in  itself, 
is  repugnant  to  his  own  will,  as  happens  in  disagreeable 
matters,  then  it  is  quite  evident  that  it  is  not  fulfilled  except 
on  account  of  the  precept.  Hence  Gregory  says  (Moral,  xxxv.) 
that  obedience  perishes  or  diminishes  when  it  holds  its  own  in 
agreeable  matters,  because,  to  wit,  one's  own  will  seems  to 


Q.  104.  Art,  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  30 

tend  principally,  not  to  the  accomplishment  of  the  precept, 
but  to  the  fulfilment  of  one's  own  desire;  but  that  it  increases 
in  disagreeable  or  difficult  matters,  because  there  one's  own  will 
tends  to  nothing  beside  the  precept.  Yet  this  must  be  under- 
stood as  regards  outward  appearances:  for,  on  the  other 
hand,  according  to  the  judgement  of  God,  Who  searches  the 
heart,  it  may  happen  that  even  in  agreeable  matters  obedi- 
ence, while  holding  its  own,  is  none  the  less  praiseworthy, 
provided  the  will  of  him  that  obeys  tend  no  less  devotedly* 
to  the  fulfilment  of  the  precept. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Reverence  regards  directly  the  person  that 
excels:  wherefore  it  admits  of  various  species  according  to 
the  various  aspects  of  excellence.  Obedience,  on  the  other 
hand,  regards  the  precept  of  the  person  that  excels,  and 
therefore  admits  of  only  one  aspect.  And  since  obedience 
is  due  to  a  person's  precept  on  account  of  reverence  to  him, 
it  follows  that  obedience  to  a  man  is  of  one  species,  though 
the  causes  from  which  it  proceeds  differ  specifically. 

/ 

Third  Article. 

whether  obedience  is  the  greatest  of  the  virtues  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  obedience  is  the  greatest  of  the 
virtues.  For  it  is  written  (1  Kings  xv.  22) :  Obedience  is 
better  than  sacrifices.  Now  the  offering  of  sacrifices  belongs 
to  religion,  which  is  the  greatest  of  all  moral  virtues,  as  shown 
above  (Q.  LXXXL,  A.  6).  Therefore  obedience  is  the 
greatest  of  all  virtues. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Gregory  says  {Moral,  xxxv.)  that  obedi- 
ence is  the  only  virtue  that  ingrafts  virtues  in  the  soul  and  pro- 
tects them  when  ingrafted.  Now  the  cause  is  greater  than  the 
effect.     Therefore  obedience  is  greater  than  all  the  virtues. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Gregory  says  {Moral,  xxxv.)  that  evil 
should  never  be  done  out  of  obedience :  yet  sometimes  for  the 
sake  of  obedience  we  should  lay  aside  the  good  we  are  doing. 
Now  one  does  not  lay  aside  a  thing  except  for  something 

*  Cf.  Q.  LXXXIL,  A.  2. 


31  OBEDIENCE  Q.  104.  Art.  3 

better.  Therefore  obedience,  for  whose  sake  the  good  of 
other  virtues  is  set  aside,  is  better  than  other  virtues. 

On  the  contrary,  Obedience  deserves  praise  because  it 
proceeds  from  charity:  for  Gregory  says  {Moral,  xxxv.)  that 
obedience  should  be  practised,  not  out  of  servile  fear,  but  from 
a  sense  of  charity,  not  through  fear  of  punishment,  but  through 
love  of  justice.  Therefore  charity  is  a  greater  virtue  than 
obedience. 

/  answer  that,  Just  as  sin  consists  in  man  contemning  God 
and  adhering  to  mutable  things,  so  the  merit  of  a  virtuous 
act  consists  in  man  contemning  created  goods  and  adhering 
to  God  as  his  end.  Now  the  end  is  greater  than  that  which 
is  directed  to  the  end.  Therefore  if  a  man  contemns  created 
goods  in  order  that  he  may  adhere  to  God,  his  virtue  derives 
greater  praise  from  his  adhering  to  God  than  from  his  con- 
temning earthly  things.  And  so  those,  namely  the  theo- 
logical, virtues  whereby  he  adheres  to  God  in  Himself,  are 
greater  than  the  moral  virtues,  whereby  he  holds  in  contempt 
some  earthly  thing  in  order  to  adhere  to  God. 

Among  the  moral  virtues,  the  greater  the  thing  which  a 
man  contemns  that  he  may  adhere  to  God,  the  greater  the 
virtue.  Now  there  are  three  kinds  of  human  goods  that  man 
may  contemn  for  God's  sake.  The  lowest  of  these  are  ex- 
ternal goods,  the  goods  of  the  body  take  the  middle  place,  and 
the  highest  are  the  goods  of  the  soul;  and  among  these  the 
chief,  in  a  way,  is  the  will,  in  so  far  as,  by  his  will,  man  makes 
use  of  all  other  goods.  Therefore,  properly  speaking,  the 
virtue  of  obedience,  whereby  we  contemn  our  own  will  for 
God's  sake,  is  more  praiseworthy  than  the  other  moral 
virtues,  which  contemn  other  goods  for  the  sake  of  God. 

Hence  Gregory  says  {Moral,  xxxv.)  that  obedience  is  rightly 
preferred  to  sacrifices,  because  by  sacrifices  another's  body  is 
slain,  whereas  by  obedience  we  slay  our  own  will.  Wherefore 
even  any  other  acts  of  virtue  are  meritorious  before  God 
through  being  performed  out  of  obedience  to  God's  will. 
For  were  one  to  suffer  even  martyrdom,  or  to  give  all  one's 
goods  to  the  poor,  unless  one  directed  these  things  to  the 
fulfilment    of    the  divine  will,  which  pertains  directly  to 


Q.io4.Art.3    THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  32 

obedience,  they  could  not  be  meritorious :  as  neither  would 
they  be  if  they  were  done  without  charity,  which  cannot 
exist  apart  from  obedience.  For  it  is  written  (r  John  ii.  4,  5) : 
He  who  saith  that  he  knoweth  God,  and  keepeth  not  His  com- 
mandments, is  a  liar  .  .  .  but  he  that  keepeth  His  word,  in  him 
in  very  deed  the  charity  of  God  is  perfected :  and  this  because 
friendship  makes  the  same  liking  and  disliking. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Obedience  proceeds  from  reverence,  which 
pays  worship  and  honour  to  a  superior,  and  in  this  respect 
it  is  contained  under  different  virtues,  although  considered 
in  itself,  as  regarding  the  aspect  of  precept,  it  is  one  special 
virtue.  Accordingly,  in  so  far  as  it  proceeds  from  reverence 
for  a  superior,  it  is  contained,  in  a  way,  under  observance; 
while  in  so  far  as  it  proceeds  from  reverence  for  one's  parents, 
it  is  contained  under  piety;  and  in  so  far  as  it  proceeds  from 
reverence  for  God,  it  comes  under  religion,  and  pertains  to 
devotion,  which  is  the  principal  act  of  religion.  Wherefore 
from  this  point  of  view  it  is  more  praiseworthy  to  obey  God 
than  to  offer  sacrifice,  as  well  as  because,  in  a  sacrifice  we 
slay  another's  body,  whereas  by  obedience  we  slay  our  own  will, 
as  Gregory  says  (loc.  cit.).  As  to  the  special  case  in  which 
Samuel  spoke,  it  would  have  been  better  for  Saul  to  obey  God 
than  to  offer  in  sacrifice  the  fat  animals  of  the  Amalekites 
against  the  commandment  of  God. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  All  acts  of  virtue,  in  so  far  as  they  come  under 
a  precept,  belong  to  obedience.  Wherefore  according  as 
acts  of  virtue  act  causally  or  dispositively  towards  their 
generation  and  preservation,  obedience  is  said  to  ingraft  and 
protect  all  virtues.  And  yet  it  does  not  follow  that  obedience 
takes  precedence  of  all  virtues  absolutely,  for  two  reasons. 
First,  because  though  an  act  of  virtue  come  under  a  precept, 
one  may  nevertheless  perform  that  act  of  virtue  without 
considering  the  aspect  of  precept.  Consequently,  if  there 
be  any  virtue,  whose  object  is  naturally  prior  to  the  precept, 
that  virtue  is  said  to  be  naturally  prior  to  obedience.  Such 
a  virtue  is  faith,  whereby  we  come  to  know  the  sublime 
nature  of  divine  authority,  by  reason  of  which  the  power  to 
command  is  competent  to  God.     Secondly,  because  infusion 


33  OBEDIENCE  Q.  ro4.  Art.  4 

of  grace  and  virtues  may  precede,  even  in  point  of  time,  all 
virtuous  acts:  and  in  this  way  obedience  is  not  prior  to  all 
virtues,  neither  in  point  of  time  nor  by  nature. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  There  are  two  kinds  of  good.  There  is  that 
to  which  we  are  bound  of  necessity,  for  instance  to  love  God, 
and  so  forth :  and  by  no  means  may  such  a  good  be  set  aside 
on  account  of  obedience.  But  there  is  another  good  to 
which  man  is  not  bound  of  necessity,  and  this  good  we  ought 
sometimes  to  set  aside  for  the  sake  of  obedience  to  which  we 
are  bound  of  necessity,  since  we  ought  not  to  do  good  by 
falling  into  sin.  Yet  as  Gregory  remarks  (ibid.),  he  who 
forbids  his  subjects  any  single  good,  must  needs  allow  them 
many  others,  lest  the  souls  of  those  who  obey  perish  utterly  from 
starvation,  through  being  deprived  of  every  good.  Thus  the 
loss  of  one  good  may  be  compensated  by  obedience  and  other 
goods. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  god  ought  to  be  obeyed  in  all  things  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  A  Hide  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  God  need  not  be  obeyed  in  all 
things.  For  it  is  written  (Matth.  ix.  30,  31)  that  Our  Lord 
after  healing  the  two  blind  men  commanded  them,  saying: 
See  that  no  man  know  this.  But  they  going  out  spread  His 
fame  abroad  in  all  that  country.  Yet  they  are  not  blamed 
for  so  doing.  Therefor0  it  seems  that  we  are  not  bound  to 
obey  God  in  all  things. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  No  one  is  bound  to  do  anything  contrary 
to  virtue.  Now  we  find  that  God  commanded  certain  things 
contrary  to  virtue:  thus  He  commanded  Abraham  to  slay 
his  innocent  son  (Gen.  xxii.);  and  the  Jews  to  steal  the 
property  of  the  Egyptians  (Exod.  xi.),  which  things  are 
contrary  to  justice;  and  Osee  to  take  to  himself  a  woman 
who  was  an  adulteress  (Osee  hi.),  and  this  is  contrary  to 
chastity.     Therefore  God  is  not  to  be  obeyed  in  all  things. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Whoever  obeys   God  conforms  his  will 
to  the  divine  will  even  as  to  the  thing  willed.     But  we  are 
not  bound  in  all  things  to  conform  our  will  to  the  divine 
11.  ii.  4  3 


Q.  104.  Art,  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  34 

will  as  to  the  thing  willed,  as  stated  above  (I.-II.,  Q.  XIX., 
A.  10).  Therefore  man  is  not  bound  to  obey  God  in  all 
things. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Exod.  xxiv.  7) :  All  things 
thai  the  Lord  hath  spoken  we  will  do,  and  we  will  be  obedient. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  1),  he  who  obeys  is 
moved  by  the  command  of  the  person  he  obeys,  just  as 
natural  things  are  moved  by  their  motive  causes.  Now 
just  as  God  is  the  first  mover  of  all  things  that  are  moved 
naturally,  so  too  is  He  the  first  mover  of  all  wills,  as  shown 
above  (I.-II.,  Q.  IX.,  A.  6).  Therefore  just  as  all  natural 
things  are  subject  to  the  divine  motion  by  a  natural  neces- 
sity, so  too  all  wills,  by  a  kind  of  necessity  of  justice,  are 
bound  to  obey  the  divine  command. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Our  Lord  in  telling  the  blind  men  to  conceal 
the  miracle  had  no  intention  of  binding  them  with  the  force 
of  a  divine  precept,  but,  as  Gregory  says  (Moral,  xix.),  gave 
an  example  to  His  servants  ivho  follow  Him,  that  they  might 
wish  to  hide  their  virtue  and  yet  that  it  should  be  proclaimed 
against  their  will,  in  order  that  others  might  profit  by  their 
example. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Even  as  God  does  nothing  contrary  to  nature 
(since  the  nature  of  a  thing  is  what  God  does  therein,  according 
to  a  gloss  on  Rom.  xi.),  and  yet  does  certain  things  contrary 
to  the  wonted  course  of  nature;  so  too  God  can  command 
nothing  contrary  to  virtue,  since  virtue  and  rectitude  of 
human  will  consist  chiefly  in  conformity  with  God's  will  and 
obedience  to  His  command,  although  it  be  contrary  to  the 
wonted  mode  of  virtue.  Accordingly,  then,  the  command 
given  to  Abraham  to  slay  his  innocent  son  was  not  contrary 
to  justice,  since  God  is  the  author  of  life  and  death.  Nor 
again  was  it  contrary  to  justice  that  He  commanded  the 
Jews  to  take  things  belonging  to  the  Egyptians,  because  all 
things  are  His,  and  He  gives  them  to  whom  He  will.  Nor 
was  it  contrary  to  chastity  that  Osee  was  commanded  to  take 
an  adulteress,  because  God  Himself  is  the  ordainer  of  human 
generation,  and  the  right  manner  of  intercourse  with  woman 
is  that  which  He  appoints.     Hence  it  is  evident  that  the 


35  OBEDIENCE  Q.  104.  Art.  5 

persons  aforesaid  did  not  sin,  neither  by  obeying  God  nor 
by  willing  to  obey  Him. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Though  man  is  not  always  bound  to  will 
what  God  wills,  yet  he  is  always  bound  to  will  what  God 
wills  him  to  will.  This  comes  to  man's  knowledge  chiefly 
through  God's  command,  wherefore  man  is  bound  to  obey 
God's  commands  in  all  things. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  subjects  are  bound  to  obey  their 
superiors  in  all  things  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  subjects  are  bound  to  obey  their 
superiors  in  all  things.  For  the  Apostle  says  (Coloss.  iii.  20)  : 
Children,  obey  your  parents  in  all  things,  and  farther  on 
(verse  22) :  Servants,  obey  in  all  things  your  masters  according 
to  the  flesh.  Therefore  in  like  manner  other  subjects  are 
bound  to  obey  their  superiors  in  all  things. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Superiors  stand  between  God  and  their 
subjects,  according  to  Deut.  v.  5,  I  was  the  mediator  and 
stood  between  the  Lord  and  you  at  that  time,  to  show  you  His 
words.  Now  there  is  no  going  from  extreme  to  extreme, 
except  through  that  which  stands  between.  Therefore  the 
commands  of  a  superior  must  be  esteemed  the  commands  of 
God,  wherefore  the  Apostle  says  (Gal.  iv.  14) :  You  ...  re- 
ceived me  as  an  angel  of  God,  even  as  Christ  Jesus,  and 
(1  Thess.  ii.  13) :  When  you  had  received  of  us  the  word  of  the 
hearing  of  God,  you  received  it,  not  as  the  word  of  men,  butf  as  it 
is  indeed,  the  word  of  God.  Therefore  as  man  is  bound  to  obey 
God  in  all  things,  so  is  he  bound  to  obey  his  superiors. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Just  as  religious  in  making  their  profes- 
sion take  vows  of  chastity  and  poverty,  so  do  they  also  vow 
obedience.  Now  a  religious  is  bound  to  observe  chastity 
and  poverty  in  all  things.  Therefore  he  is  also  bound  to 
obey  in  all  things. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Acts  v.  29) :  We  ought  to  obey 
God  rather  than  men.     Now^sometimes  the  things  commanded 


Q.  104.  Art.  5    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  36 

by  a  superior  are  against  God.     Therefore  superiors  are  not 
to  be  obeyed  in  all  things. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (AA.  1.  4),  he  who  obeys 
is  moved  at  the  bidding  of  the  person  who  commands  him, 
by  a  certain  necessity  of  justice,  even  as  a  natural  thing  is 
moved  through  the  power  of  its  mover  by  a  natural  necessity. 
That  a  natural  thing  be  not  moved  by  its  mover,  may 
happen  in  two  ways.  First,  on  account  of  a  hindrance 
arising  from  the  stronger  power  of  some  other  mover ;  thus 
wood  is  not  burnt  by  fire  if  a  stronger  force  of  water  inter- 
vene. Secondly,  through  lack  of  order  in  the  movable 
with  regard  to  its  mover,  since,  though  it  is  subject  to  the 
latter 's  action  in  one  respect,  yet  it  is  not  subject  thereto 
in  every  respect.  Thus,  a  humour  is  sometimes  subject  to 
the  action  of  heat,  as  regards  being  heated,  but  not  as 
regards  being  dried  up  or  consumed.  In  like  manner  there 
are  two  reasons,  for  which  a  subject  may  not  be  bound  to 
obey  his  superior  in  all  things.  First  on  account  of  the 
command  of  a  higher  power.  For  as  a  gloss  says  on  Rom. 
xiii.  2,  They  that  resist  (Vulg., — He  that  resisteth)  the  power, 
resist  the  ordinance  of  God  (cf.  S.  Augustine,  De  Verb. 
Dom.  viii.).  //  a  commissioner  issue  an  order,  are  you  to 
comply,  if  it  is  contrary  to  the  bidding  of  the  proconsul  ?  Again 
if  the  proconsul  command  one  thing  and  the  emperor  another, 
will  you  hesitate  to  disregard  the  former  and  serve  the  latter  ? 
Therefore  if  the  emperor  commands  one  thing  and  God  another, 
you  must  disregard  the  former  and  obey  God.  Secondly,  a 
subject  is  not  bound  to  obey  his  superior,  if  the  latter  com- 
mand him  to  do  something  wherein  he  is  not  subject  to 
him.  For  Seneca  says  (De  Beneficiis  iii.):  It  is  wrong  to 
suppose  that  slavery  falls  upon  the  whole  man  :  for  the  better 
part  of  him  is  excepted.  His  body  is  subjected  and  assigned 
to  his  master,  but  his  soul  is  his  own.  Consequently  in  matters 
touching  the  internal  movement  of  the  will  man  is  not 
bound  to  obey  his  fellow-man,  but  God  alone. 

Nevertheless  man  is  bound  to  obey  his  fellow-man  in 
things  that  have  to  be  done  externally  by  means  of  the  body : 
and  yet,  since  by  nature  all  men  are  equal,  he  is  not  bound 


37  OBEDIENCE  Q.  104.  Art.  5 

to  obey  another  man  in  matters  touching  the  nature  of  the 
body,  for  instance  in  those  relating  to  the  support  of  his 
body  or  the  begetting  of  his  children.  Wherefore  servants 
are  not  bound  to  obey  their  masters,  nor  children  their 
parents,  in  the  question  of  contracting  marriage  or  of  re- 
maining in  the  state  of  virginity  or  the  like.  But  in  matters 
concerning  the  disposal  of  actions  and  human  affairs,  a 
subject  is  bound  to  obey  his  superior  within  the  sphere  of 
his  authority;  for  instance  a  soldier  must  obey  his  general 
in  matters  relating  to  war,  a  servant  his  master  in  matters 
touching  the  execution  of  the  duties  of  his  service,  a  son  his 
father  in  matters  relating  to  the  conduct  of  his  life  and  the 
care  of  the  household;  and  so  forth. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  When  the  Apostle  says  in  all  things,  he 
refers  to  matters  within  the  sphere  of  a  father's  or  master's 
authority. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Man  is  subject  to  God  simply  as  regards 
all  things,  both  internal  and  external,  wherefore  he  is  bound 
to  obey  Him  in  all  things.  On  the  other  hand,  inferiors  are 
not  subject  to  their  superiors  in  all  things,  but  only  in  certain 
things  and  in  a  particular  way,  in  respect  of  which  the  superior 
stands  between  God  and  his  subjects,  whereas  in  respect 
of  other  matters  the  subject  is  immediately  under  God,  by 
Whom  he  is  taught  either  by  the  natural  or  by  the  written  law. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Religious  profess  obedience  as  to  the  regular 
mode  of  life,  in  respect  of  which  they  are  subject  to  their 
superiors :  wherefore  they  are  bound  to  obey  in  those  matters 
only  which  may  belong  to  the  regular  mode  of  life,  and  this 
obedience  suffices  for  salvation.  If  they  be  willing  to  obey 
even  in  other  matters,  this  will  belong  to  the  superabundance 
of  perfection;  provided,  however,  such  things  be  not  contrary 
to  God  or  to  the  rule  they  profess,  for  obedience  in  this  case 
would  be  unlawful. 

Accordingly  we  may  distinguish  a  threefold  obedience ;  one, 
sufficient  for  salvation,  and  consisting  in  obeying  when 
one  is  bound  to  obey:  secondly,  perfect  obedience,  which 
obeys  in  all  things  lawful:  thirdly,  indiscreet  obedience, 
which  obeys  even  in  matters  unlawful. 


O.  104.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  38 


Sixth  Article, 
whether  christians  are  bound  to  obey  the  secular 

POWER  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  Christians  are  not  bound  to 
obey  the  secular  power.  For  a  gloss  on  Matth.  xvii.  25, 
Then  the  children  are  free,  says:  //  in  every  kingdom  the 
children  of  the  king  who  holds  sway  over  that  kingdom  are  free, 
then  the  children  of  that  King,  under  Whose  sway  are  all 
kingdoms,  should  be  free  in  every  kingdom.  Now  Christians, 
by  their  faith  in  Christ,  are  made  children  of  God,  according 
to  John  i.  12 :  He  gave  them  power  to  be  made  the  so7is  of  God, 
to  them  that  believe  in  His  name.  Therefore  they  are  not 
bound  to  obey  the  secular  power. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  It  is  written  (Rom.  vii.  4) :  You  .  .  .  are 
become  dead  to  the  law  by  the  body  of  Christ,  and  the  law 
mentioned  here  is  the  divine  law  of  the  Old  Testament. 
Now  human  law  whereby  men  are  subject  to  the  secular 
power  is  of  less  account  than  the  divine  law  of  the  Old  Testa- 
ment. Much  more,  therefore,  since  they  have  become 
members  of  Christ's  body,  are  men  freed  from  the  law  of 
subjection,  whereby  they  were  under  the  power  of  secular 
princes. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Men  are  not  bound  to  obey  robbers,  who 
oppress  them  with  violence.  Now,  Augustine  says  (De 
Civ.  Dei  iv.) :  Without  justice,  what  else  is  a  kingdom  but 
a  huge  robbery  ?  Since  therefore  the  authority  of  secular 
princes  is  frequently  exercised  with  injustice,  or  owes  its 
origin  to  some  unjust  usurpation,  it  seems  that  Christians 
ought  not  to  obey  secular  princes. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Tit.  iii.  1):  Admonish  them 
to  be  subject  to  princes  and  powers,  and  (1  Pet.  ii.  13,  14) :  Be 
ye  subject .  .  .  to  every  human  creature  for  God' s  sake  :  whether 
it  be  to  the  king  as  excelling,  or  to  governors  as  sent  by  him. 

I  answer  that,  Faith  in  Christ  is  the  origin  and  cause  of 
justice,  according  to  Rom.   iii.   22,  The  justice  of  God  by 


39  OBEDIENCE  Q.  104.  Art.  6 

faith  of  Jesus  Christ :  wherefore  faith  in  Christ  does  not 
void  the  order  of  justice,  but  strengthens  it.  Now  the  order 
of  justice  requires  that  subjects  obey  their  superiors,  else 
the  stability  of  human  affairs  would  cease.  Hence  faith  in 
Christ  does  not  excuse  the  faithful  from  the  obligation  of 
obeying  secular  princes. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  As  stated  above  (A.  5),  the  subjection 
whereby  one  man  is  bound  to  another  regards  the  body ;  not 
the  soul,  which  retains  its  liberty.  Now,  in  this  state  of  life 
we  are  freed  by  the  grace  of  Christ  from  defects  of  the  soul, 
but  not  from  defects  of  the  body,  as  the  Apostle  declares  by 
saying  of  himself  (Rom.  vii.  23)  that  in  his  mind  he  served 
the  law  of  God,  but  in  his  flesh  the  law  of  sin.  Wherefore 
those  that  are  made  children  of  God  by  grace  are  free  from 
the  spiritual  bondage  of  sin,  but  not  from  the  bodily 
bondage,  whereby  they  are  held  bound  to  earthly  masters, 
as  a  gloss  observes  on  1  Tim.  vi.  1,  Whosoever  are  servants 
under  the  yoke,  etc. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  Old  Law  was  a  figure  of  the  New  Testa- 
ment, and  therefore  it  had  to  cease  on  the  advent  of  truth. 
And  the  comparison  with  human  law  does  not  stand,  because 
thereby  one  man  is  subject  to  another.  Yet  man  is  bound 
by  divine  law  to  obey  his  fellow-man. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Man  is  bound  to  obey  secular  princes  in  so 
far  as  this  is  required  by  the  order  of  justice.  Wherefore  if 
the  prince's  authority  is  not  just  but  usurped,  or  if  he  com- 
mands what  is  unjust,  his  subjects  are  not  bound  to  obey 
him,  except  perhaps  accidentally,  in  order  to  avoid  scandal 
or  danger. 


QUESTION  CV. 

OF   DISOBEDIENCE. 

(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  disobedience,  under  which  head  there 
are  two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  it  is  a  mortal  sin  ? 
(2)  Whether  it  is  the  most  grievous  of  sins  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  disobedience  is  a  mortal  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  disobedience  is  not  a  mortal 
sin.     For   every   sin   is   a    disobedience,    as   appears   from 
Ambrose's  definition  given  above  (Q.  CIV.  A.  2,  Obj.  1). 
Therefore  if  disobedience  were  a  mortal  sin,  every  sin  would 
be  mortal. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Gregory  says  (Moral,  xxxi.)  that  dis- 
obedience is  born  of  vainglory.  But  vainglory  is  not  a 
mortal  sin.     Neither  therefore  is  disobedience. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  A  person  is  said  to  be  disobedient  when 
he  does  not  fulfil  a  superior's  command.  But  superiors  often 
issue  so  many  commands  that  it  is  seldom,  if  ever,  possible 
to  fulfil  them.  Therefore  if  disobedience  were  a  mortal  sin, 
it  would  follow  that  man  cannot  avoid  mortal  sin,  which  is 
absurd.     Wherefore  disobedience  is  not  a  mortal  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Those  who  are  disobedient  to  parents  are 
reckoned  (Rom.  i.  30:  2  Tim.  iii.  2)  among  other  mortal  sins. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXIV.,  A.  12:  I. -II., 
Q.  LXXIL,  A.  5:  Q.  LXXXVIII.,  A.  1),  a  mortal  sin  is  one 
that  is  contrary  to  charity  which  is  the  cause  of  spiritual 

40 


41  DISOBEDIENCE  Q.  105.  Art.  i 

life.  Now  by  charity  we  love  God  and  our  neighbour.  The 
charity  of  God  requires  that  we  obey  His  commandments, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XXIV.,  A.  12).  Therefore  to  be  dis- 
obedient to  the  commandments  of  God  is  a  mortal  sin, 
because  it  is  contrary  to  the  love  of  God. 

Again,  the  commandments  of  God  contain  the  precept 
of  obedience  to  superiors.  Wherefore  also  disobedience  to 
the  commands  of  a  superior  is  a  mortal  sin,  as  being  contrary 
to  the  love  of  God,  according  to  Rom.  xiii.  2,  He  that  resisteth 
the  power,  resisteth  the  ordinance  of  God.  It  is  also  contrary 
to  the  love  of  our  neighbour,  as  it  withdraws  from  the 
superior  who  is  our  neighbour  the  obedience  that  is  his  due. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  definition  given  by  Ambrose  refers  to 
mortal  sin,  which  has  the  character  of  perfect  sin.  Venial  sin 
is  not  disobedience,  because  it  is  not  contrary  to  a  precept, 
but  beside  it.  Nor  again  is  every  mortal  sin  disobedience, 
properly  and  essentially,  but  only  when  one  contemns 
a  precept,  since  moral  acts  take  their  species  from  the  end. 
And  when  a  thing  is  done  contrary  to  a  precept,  not  in  con- 
tempt of  the  precept,  but  with  some  other  purpose,  it  is  not 
a  sin  of  disobedience  except  materially,  and  belongs  formally 
to  another  species  of  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Vainglory  desires  display  of  excellence. 
And  since  it  seems  to  point  to  a  certain  excellence  that  one 
be  not  subject  to  another's  command,  it  follows  that  dis- 
obedience arises  from  vainglory.  But  there  is  nothing  to 
hinder  mortal  sin  from  arising  out  of  venial  sin,  since  venial 
sin  is  a  disposition  to  mortal. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  No  one  is  bound  to  do  the  impossible: 
wherefore  if  a  superior  makes  a  heap  of  precepts  and  lays 
them  upon  his  subjects,  so  that  they  are  unable  to  fulfil 
them,  they  are  excused  from  sin.  Wherefore  superiors 
should  refrain  from  making  a  multitude  of  precepts. 


Q.io5.Art.2    THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  42 

Second  Article, 
whether  disobedience   is  the  most  grievous  of  sins  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  disobedience  is  the  most 
grievous  of  sins.  For  it  is  written  (1  Kings  xv.  23) :  It  is  like 
the  sin  of  witchcraft  to  rebel,  and  like  the  crime  of  idolatry  to 
refuse  to  obey.  But  idolatry  is  the  most  grievous  of  sins, 
as  stated  above  (O.  XCIV.,  A.  3).  Therefore  disobedience 
is  the  most  grievous  of  sins. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  sin  against  the  Holy  Ghost  is  one 
that  removes  the  obstacles  of  sin,  as  stated  above  (0.  XIV., 
A.  2).  Now  disobedience  makes  a  man  contemn  a  precept 
which,  more  than  anything,  prevents  a  man  from  sinning. 
Therefore  disobedience  is  a  sin  against  the  Holy  Ghost, 
and  consequently  is  the  most  grievous  of  sins. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  v.  19)  that  by 
the  disobedience  of  one  man,  many  were  made  sinners.  Now 
the  cause  is  seemingly  greater  than  its  effect.  Therefore 
disobedience  seems  to  be  a  more  grievous  sin  than  the  others 
that  are  caused  thereby. 

On  the  contrary,  Contempt  of  the  commander  is  a  more 
grievous  sin  than  contempt  of  his  command.  Now  some 
sins  are  against  the  very  person  of  the  commander,  such  as 
blasphemy  and  murder.  Therefore  disobedience  is  not  the 
most  grievous  of  sins. 

/  answer  that,  Not  every  disobedience  is  equally  a  sin :  for 
one  disobedience  may  be  greater  than  another,  in  two  ways. 
First,  on  the  part  of  the  superior  commanding,  since, 
although  a  man  should  take  even7  care  to  obey  each  superior, 
yet  it  is  a  greater  duty  to  obey  a  higher  than  a  lower  authority, 
in  sign  of  which  the  command  of  a  lower  authority  is  set 
aside  if  it  be  contrary  to  the  command  of  a  higher  authority. 
Consequently  the  higher  the  person  who  commands,  the  more 
grievous  is  it  to  disobey  him:  so  that  it  is  more  grievous  to 
disobey  God  than  man.  Secondly,  on  the  part  of  the  things 
commanded.     For  the  person  commanding  does  not  equally 


43  DISOBEDIENCE  Q.  105.  Art.  2 

desire  the  fulfilment  of  all  his  commands:  since  every  such 
person  desires  above  all  the  end,  and  that  which  is  nearest 
to  the  end.  Wherefore  disobedience  is  the  more  grievous, 
according  as  the  unfulfilled  commandment  is  more  in  the 
intention  of  the  person  commanding.  As  to  the  command- 
ments of  God,  it  is  evident  that  the  greater  the  good  com- 
manded, the  more  grievous  the  disobedience  of  that  com- 
mandment, because  since  God's  will  is  essentially  directed 
to  the  good,  the  greater  the  good,  the  more  does  God  wish 
it  to  be  fulfilled.  Consequently  he  that  disobeys  the  com- 
mandment of  the  love  of  God  sins  more  grievously  than  one 
who  disobeys  the  commandment  of  the  love  of  our  neighbour. 
On  the  other  hand,  man's  will  is  not  always  directed  to  the 
greater  good :  hence,  when  we  are  bound  by  a  mere  precept 
of  man,  a  sin  is  more  grievous,  not  through  setting  aside  a 
greater  good,  but  through  setting  aside  that  which  is  more 
in  the  intention  of  the  person  commanding. 

Accordingly  the  various  degrees  of  disobedience  must 
correspond  with  the  various  degrees  of  precepts:  because 
the  disobedience  in  which  there  is  contempt  of  God's  precept, 
from  the  very  nature  of  disobedience  is  more  grievous  than 
a  sin  committed  against  a  man,  apart  from  the  latter  being 
a  disobedience  to  God.  And  I  say  this  because  whoever 
sins  against  his  neighbour  acts  also  against  God's  command- 
ment.— And  if  the  divine  precept  be  contemned  in  a  yet 
graver  matter,  the  sin  is  still  more  grievous.  The  dis- 
obedience that  contains  contempt  of  a  man's  precept  is  less 
grievous  than  the  sin  which  contemns  the  man  who  made 
the  precept,  because  reverence  for  the  person  commanding 
should  give  rise  to  reverence  for  his  command.  In  like 
manner  a  sin  that  directly  involves  contempt  of  God,  such 
as  blasphemy,  or  the  like,  is  more  grievous  (even  if  we 
mentally  separate  the  disobedience  from  the  sin)  than  would 
be  a  sin  involving  contempt  of  God's  commandment  alone. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  comparison  of  Samuel's  is  one,  not  of 
equality  but  of  likeness,  because  disobedience  redounds  to 
the  contempt  of  God,  just  as  idolatry  does,  though  the  latter 
does  so  more. 


Q.  105.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  44 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Not  every  disobedience  is  a  sin  against  the 
Holy  Ghost,  but  only  that  to  which  obstinacy  is  added :  for 
it  is  not  the  contempt  of  any  obstacle  to  sin  that  constitutes 
sin  against  the  Holy  Ghost,  else  the  contempt  of  any  good 
would  be  a  sin  against  the  Holy  Ghost,  since  any  good  may 
hinder  a  man  from  committing  sin.  The  sin  against  the 
Holy  Ghost  consists  in  the  contempt  of  those  goods  which 
lead  directly  to  repentance  and  the  remission  of  sins. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  first  sin  of  our  first  parent,  from  which 
sin  was  transmitted  to  all  men,  was  not  disobedience  con- 
sidered as  a  special  sin,  but  pride,  from  which  the  man  pro- 
ceeded to  disobey.  Hence  the  Apostle  in  these  words  seems 
to  take  disobedience  in  its  relation  to  every  sin. 


QUESTION  CVI 

OF  THANKFULNESS  OR  GRATITUDE. 

(In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  thankfulness  or  gratitude,  and 
ingratitude.  Concerning  thankfulness  there  are  six  points  of 
inquiry:  (i)  Whether  thankfulness  is  a  special  virtue  distinct 
from  other  virtues  ?  (2)  Who  owes  more  thanks  to  God, 
the  innocent  or  the  penitent  ?  (3)  Whether  man  is  always 
bound  to  give  thanks  for  human  favours  ?  (4)  Whether 
thanksgiving  should  be  deferred  ?  (5)  Whether  thanks- 
giving should  be  measured  according  to  the  favour  received 
or  the  disposition  of  the  giver  ?  (6)  Whether  one  ought  to 
pay  back  more  than  one  has  received  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  thankfulness  is  a  special  virtue, 
distinct  from  other  virtues  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  thankfulness  is  not  a  special 
virtue,  distinct  from  other  virtues.  For  we  have  received 
the  greatest  benefits  from  God,  and  from  our  parents.  Now 
the  honour  which  we  pay  to  God  in  return  belongs  to  the 
virtue  of  religion,  and  the  honour  with  which  we  repay  our 
parents  belongs  to  the  virtue  of  piety.  Therefore  thank- 
fulness or  gratitude  is  not  distinct  from  the  other  virtues. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Proportionate  repayment  belongs  to  com- 
mutative justice,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  v.  4). 
Now  the  purpose  of  giving  thanks  is  repayment  (ibid.). 
Therefore  thanksgiving,  which  belongs  to  gratitude,  is  an 

45 


Q  106.  Art.  i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  46 

act  of  justice.  Therefore  gratitude  is  not  a  special  virtue, 
distinct  from  other  virtues. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Acknowledgement  of  favour  received  is 
requisite  for  the  preservation  of  friendship,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  {Ethic,  viii.  13 ;  ix.  1).  Now  friendship  is  associated 
with  all  the  virtues,  since  they  are  the  reason  for  which  man 
is  loved.  Therefore  thankfulness  or  gratitude,  to  which 
it  belongs  to  repay  favours  received,  is  not  a  special  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  reckons  thankfulness  a  special  part 
of  justice  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.). 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LX.,  A.  3),  the 
nature  of  the  debt  to  be  paid  must  needs  vary  according  to 
various  causes  giving  rise  to  the  debt,  yet  so  that  the  greater 
always  includes  the  lesser.  Now  the  cause  of  debt  is  found 
primarily  and  chiefly  in  God,  in  that  He  is  the  first  principle 
of  all  our  goods :  secondarily  it  is  found  in  our  father,  because 
he  is  the  proximate  principle  of  our  begetting  and  upbring- 
ing: thirdty  it  is  found  in  the  person  that  excels  in  dignity, 
from  whom  general  favours  proceed;  fourthly  it  is  found  in 
a  benefactor,  from  whom  we  have  received  particular  and 
private  favours,  on  account  of  which  we  are  under  par- 
ticular obligation  to  him. 

Accordingly,  since  what  we  owe  God,  or  our  father,  or  a 
person  excelling  in  dignity,  is  not  the  same  as  what  we  owe 
a  benefactor  from  whom  we  have  received  some  particular 
favour,  it  follows  that  after  religion,  whereby  we  pay  God 
due  worship,  and  piety,  whereby  we  worship  our  parents, 
and  observance,  whereby  we  worship  persons  excelling  in 
dignity,  there  is  thankfulness  or  gratitude,  whereby  we  give 
thanks  to  our  benefactors.  And  it  is  distinct  from  the 
foregoing  virtues,  just  as  each  of  these  is  distinct  from  the 
one  that  precedes,  as  falling  short  thereof. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Just  as  religion  is  superexcelling  piety,  so 
is  it  excelling  thankfulness  or  gratitude:  wherefore  giving 
thanks  to  God  was  reckoned  above  (Q.  LXXXIIL,  A.  17) 
among  things  pertaining  to  religion. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Proportionate  repayment  belongs  to  commu- 
tative justice,  when  it  answers  to  the  legal  due;  for  instance 


47  THANKFULNESS  Q.  106.  Art.  2 

when  it  is  contracted  that  so  much  be  paid  for  so  much. 
But  the  repayment  that  belongs  to  the  virtue  of  thankful- 
ness or  gratitude  answers  to  the  moral  debt,  and  is  paid 
spontaneously.  Hence  thanksgiving  is  less  thankful  when 
compelled,  as  Seneca  observes  (De  Beneficiis  hi.). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Since  true  friendship  is  based  on  virtue, 
whatever  there  is  contrary  to  virtue  in  a  friend  is  an  obstacle 
to  friendship,  and  whatever  in  him  is  virtuous  is  an  incentive 
to  friendship.  In  this  way  friendship  is  preserved  by  re- 
payment of  favours,  although  repayment  of  favours  belongs 
specially  to  the  virtue  of  gratitude. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  innocent  is  more  bound  to  give 
thanks  to  god  than  the  penitent  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  innocent  is  more  bound 
to  give  thanks  to  God  than  the  penitent.  For  the  greater 
the  gift  one  has  received  from  God,  the  more  is  one  bound 
to  give  Him  thanks.  Now  the  gift  of  innocence  is  greater 
than  that  of  justice  restored.  Therefore  it  seems  that  the 
innocent  is  more  bound  to  give  thanks  to  God  than  the 
penitent. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  A  man  owes  love  to  his  benefactor 
just  as  he  owes  him  gratitude.  Now  Augustine  says 
(Conf.  ii.) :  What  man,  weighing  his  own  infirmity,  would  dare 
to  ascribe  his  purity  and  innocence  to  his  own  strength;  that 
so  he  should  love  Thee  the  less,  as  if  he  had  less  needed  Thy 
mercy,  whereby  Thou  remittest  sins  to  those  that  turn  to  Thee  ? 
And  farther  on  he  says:  And  for  this  let  him  love  Thee  as 
much,  yea  and  more,  since  by  Whom  he  sees  me  to  have  been 
recovered  from  such  deep  torpor  of  sin,  by  Him  he  sees  himself 
to  have  been  from  the  like  torpor  of  sin  preserved.  Therefore 
the  innocent  is  also  more  bound  to  give  thanks  than  the 
penitent. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  more  a  gratuitous  favour  is  con- 
tinuous, the  greater  the  thanksgiving  due  for  it.     Now  the 


Q.  io6.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  48 

favour  of  divine  grace  is  more  continuous  in  the  innocent 
than  in  the  penitent.  For  Augustine  says  (ibid.):  To  Thy 
grace  I  ascribe  it,  and  to  Thy  mercy,  that  Thou  hast  melted 
away  my  sins  as  it  were  ice  To  Thy  grace  I  ascribe  also  what- 
soever I  have  not  done  of  evil ;  for  what  might  I  not  have  done  ? 
.  .  .  Yea,  all  I  confess  to  have  been  forgiven  me,  both  what 
evils  I  committed  by  my  own  wilfulness,  and  what  by  Thy 
guidance  I  committed  not.  Therefore  the  innocent  is  more 
bound  to  give  thanks  than  the  penitent. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Luke  vii.  47) :  To  whom 
more  is  forgiven,  he  loveth  more*  Therefore  for  the  same 
reason  he  is  bound  to  greater  thanksgiving. 

/  answer  that,  Thanksgiving  (gratiarum  actio)  in  the 
recipient  corresponds  to  the  favour  (gratia)  of  the  giver: 
so  that  when  there  is  greater  favour  on  the  part  of  th^  giver, 
greater  thanks  are  due  on  the  part  of  the  recipient.  Now 
a  favour  is  something  bestowed  gratis  :  wherefore  on  the 
part  of  the  giver  the  favour  may  be  greater  on  two  counts. 
First,  owing  to  the  quantity  of  the  thing  given :  and  in  this 
way  the  innocent  owes  greater  thanksgiving,  because  he 
receives  a  greater  gift  from  God,  also,  absolutely  speaking, 
a  more  continuous  gift,  other  things  being  equal.  Secondly, 
a  favour  may  be  said  to  be  greater,  because  it  is  given  more 
gratuitously ;  and  in  this  sense  the  penitent  is  more  bound  to 
give  thanks  than  the  innocent,  because  what  he  receives 
from  God  is  more  gratuitously  given :  since,  whereas  he  was 
deserving  of  punishment,  he  has  received  grace.  Where- 
fore, although  the  gift  bestowed  on  the  innocent  is,  con- 
sidered absolutely,  greater,  yet  the  gift  bestowed  on  the 
penitent  is  greater  in  relation  to  him :  even  as  a  small  gift 
bestowed  on  a  poor  man  is  greater  to  him  than  a  great  gift 
is  to  a  rich  man.  And  since  actions  are  about  singulars, 
in  matters  of  action,  we  have  to  take  note  of  what  is  such 
h  ^  and  now,  rather  than  of  what  is  such  absolu*  "dy,  as  the 
Philosopher  observes  (Ethic,  hi.)  in  treating  of  the  voluntary 
and  the  involuntary. 

This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Objections. 

*  Vulg., — To  whom  less  is  forgiven,  he  loveth  less. 


49  THANKFULNESS  Q.  106.  Art.  3 


Third  Article. 

whether  a  man  is  bound  to  give  thanks  to    every 

benefactor  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  a  man  is  not  bound  to  give 
thanks  to  every  benefactor.  For  a  man  may  benefit  himself 
just  as  he  may  harm  himself,  according  to  Ecclus.  xiv.  5, 
He  that  is  evil  to  himself,  to  whom  will  he  be  good  ?  But  a 
man  cannot  thank  himself,  since  thanksgiving  seems  to 
pass  from  one  person  to  another.  Therefore  thanksgiving 
is  not  due  to  every  benefactor. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Gratitude  is  a  repayment  of  an  act  of 
grace.  But  some  favours  are  granted  without  grace,  and 
are  rudely,  slowly  and  grudgingly  given.  Therefore  grati- 
tude is  not  always  due  to  a  benefactor. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  No  thanks  are  due  to  one  who  works  for 
his  own  profit.  But  sometimes  people  bestow  favours 
for  their  own  profit.  Therefore  thanks  are  not  due  to 
them. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  No  thanks  are  due  to  a  slave,  for  all 
that  he  is  belongs  to  his  master.  Yet  sometimes  a  slave  does 
a  good  turn  to  his  master.  Therefore  gratitude  is  not  due 
to  every  benefactor. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  No  one  is  bound  to  do  what  he  cannot 
do  equitably  and  advantageously.  Now  it  happens  at  times 
that  the  benefactor  is  very  well  off,  and  it  would  be  of  no 
advantage  to  him  to  be  repaid  for  a  favour  he  has  bestowed. 
Again  it  happens  sometimes  that  the  benefactor  from  being 
virtuous  has  become  wicked,  so  that  it  would  not  seem 
equitable  to  repay  him.  Also  the  recipient  of  a  favour  may 
be  a  poor  man,  and  is  quite  unable  to  repay.  Therefore 
seemingly  a  man  is  not  always  bound  to  repayment  for 
favours  received. 

Obj.  6.  Further,  No  one  is  bound  to  do  for  another  what 
is  inexpedient  and  hurtful  to  him.  Now  sometimes  it 
happens  that  repayment  of  a  favour  would  be  hurtful  or 

n.  ii.  4  4 


Q.  106.ART.3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  50 

useless  to  the  person  repaid.     Therefore  favours  are  not 
always  to  be  repaid  by  gratitude. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (1  Thess.  v.  18) :  In  all  things 
give  thanks. 

I  answer  that,  Every  effect  turns  naturally  to  its  cause; 
wherefore  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Nom.  i.)  that  God  turns  all 
things  to  Himself,  because  He  is  the  cause  of  all  :  for  the  effect 
must  needs  always  be  directed  to  the  end  of  the  agent. 
Now  it  is  evident  that  a  benefactor,  as  such,  is  cause  of  the 
beneficiary7.  Hence  the  natural  order  requires  that  he  who 
has  received  a  favour  should,  by  repaying  the  favour,  turn 
to  his  benefactor  according  to  the  mode  of  each.  And,  as 
stated  above  with  regard  to  a  father  (Q.  XXXI.,  A.  3: 
O.  CI.,  A.  2),  a  man  owes  his  benefactor,  as  such,  honour  and 
reverence,  since  the  latter  stands  to  him  in  the  relation  of 
principle ;  but  accidentally  he  owes  him  assistance  or  support, 
if  he  need  it. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  In  the  words  of  Seneca  (De  Benef.  v.), 
just  as  a  man  is  liberal  who  gives  not  to  himself  but  to  others, 
and  gracious  who  forgives  not  himself  but  others,  and  merciful 
who  is  moved,  not  by  his  own  misfortunes  but  by  another's 
so  too,  no  man  confers  a  favour  on  himself,  he  is  but  following 
the  bent  of  his  nature,  which  moves  him  to  resist  what  hurts 
him,  and  to  seek  what  is  profitable.  Wherefore  in  things  that 
one  does  for  oneself,  there  is  no  place  for  gratitude  or 
ingratitude,  since  a  man  cannot  deny  himself  a  thing  except 
by  keeping  it.  Nevertheless  things  which  are  properly 
spoken  of  in  relation  to  others  are  spoken  of  metaphorically 
in  relation  to  oneself,  as  the  Philosopher  states  regarding 
justice  {Ethic,  v.  n),  in  so  far,  to  wit,  as  the  various  parts  of 
man  are  considered  as  though  the}7  were  various  persons. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  is  the  mark  of  a  happy  disposition  to  see 
good  rather  than  evil.  Wherefore  if  someone  has  conferred 
a  favour,  not  as  he  ought  to  have  conferred  it,  the  recipient 
should  not  for  that  reason  withhold  his  thanks.  Yet  he  owes 
less  thanks,  than  if  the  favour  had  been  conferred  duly, 
since  in  fact  the  favour  is  less,  for,  as  Seneca  remarks  (De 
Benef.  ii.)  promptness  enhances,  delay  discounts  a  favour. 


51  THANKFULNESS  Q.  106.  Art.  3 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  Seneca  observes  (De  Bene/,  vi.),  it 
matters  much  whether  a  person  does  a  kindness  to  us  for  his 
own  sake,  or  for  ours,  or  for  both  his  and  ours.  He  that 
considers  himself  only,  and  benefits  because  he  cannot  other- 
wise benefit  himself,  seems  to  me  like  a  man  who  seeks  fodder 
for  his  cattle.  And  farther  on :  If  he  has  done  it  for  me  in 
common  with  himself,  having  both  of  us  in  his  mind,  I  am 
ungrateful  and  not  merely  unjust,  unless  I  rejoice  that  what 
was  profitable  to  him  is  profitable  to  me  also.  It  is  the  height 
of  malevolence  to  refuse  to  recognize  a  kindness,  unless  the 
giver  has  been  the  loser  thereby. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  As  Seneca  observes  [De  Benef.  iii.),  when  a 
slave  does  what  is  wont  to  be  demanded  of  a  slave,  it  is  part 
of  his  service :  when  he  does  more  than  a  slave  is  bound  to  do, 
it  is  a  favour  :  for  as  soon  as  he  does  anything  from  a  motive 
of  friendship,  if  indeed  that  be  his  motive,  it  is  no  longer 
called  service.  Wherefore  gratitude  is  due  even  to  a  slave, 
when  he  does  more  than  his  duty. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  A  poor  man  is  certainly  not  ungrateful  if 
he  does  what  he  can.  For  since  kindness  depends  on  the 
heart  rather  than  on  the  deed,  so  too  gratitude  depends 
chiefly  on  the  heart.  Hence  Seneca  says  (De  Benef.  ii.) : 
Who  receives  a  favour  gratefully,  has  already  begun  to  pay  it 
back  :  and  that  we  are  grateful  for  favours  received  should  be 
shown  by  the  outpourings  of  the  heart,  not  only  in  his  hearing 
but  everywhere.  From  this  it  is  evident  that  however  well 
off  a  man  may  be,  it  is  possible  to  thank  him  for  his  kindness 
by  showing  him  reverence  and  honour.  Wherefore  the 
Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  viii.  14)  :  He  that  abounds  should  be 
repaid  with  honour,  he  that  is  in  want  should  be  repaid  with 
money  :  and  Seneca  writes  (De  Benef.  vi.):  There  are  many 
ways  of  repaying  those  who  are  well  off,  whatever  we  happen 
to  owe  them  ;  such  as  good  advice,  frequent  fellowship,  affable 
and  pleasant  conversation  without  flattery.  Therefore  there 
is  no  need  for  a  man  to  desire  neediness  or  distress  in 
his  benefactor  before  repaying  his  kindness,  because,  as 
Seneca  says  (De  Benef.  vi.),  it  were  inhuman  to  desire  this 
in  one  from  whom  you  have  received  no  favour;  how  much 


Q.  io6.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  52 

more  so  to  desire  it  in  one  whose  kindness  has  made  you  his 
debtor  ! 

If,  however,  the  benefactor  has  lapsed  from  virtue, 
nevertheless  he  should  be  repaid  according  to  his  state, 
that  he  may  return  to  virtue  if  possible.  But  if  he  be  so 
wicked  as  to  be  incurable,  then  his  heart  has  changed,  and 
consequently  no  repayment  is  due  for  his  kindness,  as  here- 
tofore. And  yet,  as  far  as  it  is  possible  without  sin,  the 
kindness  he  has  shown  should  be  held  in  memory,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  ix.  3). 

Reply  Obj.  6.  As  stated  in  the  preceding  reply,  repay- 
ment of  a  favour  depends  chiefly  on  the  affection  of  the  heart : 
wherefore  repayment  should  be  made  in  such  a  way  as  to 
prove  most  beneficial.  If,  however,  through  the  benefactor's 
carelessness  it  prove  detrimental  to  him,  this  is  not  imputed 
to  the  person  who  repays  him,  as  Seneca  observes  (De 
Bene/,  vii.) :  It  is  my  duty  to  repay,  and  not  to  keep  back  and 
safeguard  my  repayment. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  a  man  is  bound  to  repay  a  favour  at  once  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  a  man  is  bound  to  repay  a 
favour  at  once.  For  we  are  bound  to  restore  at  once  what 
we  owe,  unless  the  term  be  fixed.  Now  there  is  no  term 
prescribed  for  the  repayment  of  favours,  and  yet  this  repay- 
ment is  a  duty,  as  stated  above  (A.  3).  Therefore  a  man  is 
bound  to  repay  a  favour  at  once. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  A  good  action  would  seem  to  be  all  the 
more  praiseworthy  according  as  it  is  done  with  greater 
earnestness.  Now  earnestness  seems  to  make  a  man  do  his 
duty  without  any  delay.  Therefore  it  is  apparently  more 
praiseworthy  to  repay  a  favour  at  once. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Seneca  says  (De  Bene/,  ii.)  that  it  is 
proper  to  a  benefactor  to  act  freely  and  quickly.  Now  repay- 
ment ought  to  equal  the  favour  received.  Therefore  it 
should  be  done  at  once. 


53  THANKFULNESS  Q.  106.  Art.  4 

On  the  contrary,  Seneca  says  (De  Bene/,  iv.) :  He  that 
hastens  to  repay,  is  animated  with  a  sense,  not  of  gratitude 
but  of  indebtedness. 

I  answer  that,  Just  as  in  conferring  a  favour  two  things 
are  to  be  considered,  namely,  the  affection  of  the  heart  and 
the  gift,  so  also  must  these  things  be  considered  in  repaying 
the  favour.  As  regards  the  affection  of  the  heart,  repayment 
should  be  made  at  once,  wherefore  Seneca  says  {De  Benef.  ii.) : 
Do  you  wish  to  repay  a  favour  ?  Receive  it  graciously.  As 
regards  the  gift,  one  ought  to  wait  until  such  a  time  as  will 
be  convenient  to  the  benefactor.  In  fact,  if  instead  of 
choosing  a  convenient  time,  one  wished  to  repay  at  once, 
favour  for  favour,  it  would  not  seem  to  be  a  virtuous,  but 
a  constrained  repayment.  For,  as  Seneca  observes  (De 
Belief,  iv.),  he  that  wishes  to  repay  too  soon,  is  an  unwilling 
debtor,  and  an  unwilling  debtor  is  ungrateful. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  A  legal  debt  must  be  paid  at  once,  else  the 
equality  of  justice  would  not  be  preserved,  if  one  kept  another's 
property  without  his  consent.  But  a  moral  debt  depends  on 
the  equity  of  the  debtor:  and  therefore  it  should  be  repaid 
in  due  time  according  as  the  rectitude  of  virtue  demands. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Earnestness  of  the  will  is  not  virtuous 
unless  it  be  regulated  by  reason ;  wherefore  it  is  not  praise- 
worthy to  forestall  the  proper  time  through  earnestness. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Favours  also  should  be  conferred  at  a 
convenient  time,  and  one  should  no  longer  delay  when  the 
convenient  time  comes;  and  the  same  is  to  be  observed  in 
repaying  favours. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  in   giving  thanks  we  should   look   at  the 
benefactor's  disposition  or  at  the  effect  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  in  repaying  favours  we  should 
not  look  at  the  benefactor's  disposition  but  at  the  effect. 
For  repayment  is  due  to  beneficence,  and  beneficence  con- 
sists in  deeds,  as  the  word  itself  denotes.  Therefore  in  re- 
paying favours  we  should  look  at  the  effect. 


Q.  106.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  54 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Thanksgiving,  whereby  we  repay  favours, 
is  a  part  of  justice.  But  justice  considers  equality  between 
giving  and  taking.  Therefore  also  in  repaying  favours  we 
should  consider  the  effect  rather  than  the  disposition  of  the 
benefactor. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  No  one  can  consider  what  he  does  not 
know.  Now  God  alone  knows  the  interior  disposition. 
Therefore  it  is  impossible  to  repay  a  favour  according  to  the 
benefactor's  disposition. 

On  the  contrary,  Seneca  says  (De  Bene/,  i.):  We  are  some- 
times under  a  greater  obligation  to  one  who  has  given  little  with 
a  large  heart,  and,  has  bestowed  a  small  favour,  yet  willingly. 

I  answer  that,  The  repayment  of  a  favour  may  belong  to 
three  virtues,  namely,  justice,  gratitude  and  friendship. 
It  belongs  to  justice  when  the  repayment  has  the  character 
of  a  legal  debt,  as  in  a  loan  and  the  like :  and  in  such  cases 
repayment  must  be  made  according  to  the  quantity  received. 

On  the  other  hand,  repayment  of  a  favour  belongs,  though 
in  different  ways,  to  friendship  and  likewise  to  the  virtue 
of  gratitude  when  it  has  the  character  of  a  moral  debt. 
For  in  the  repayment  of  friendship  we  have  to  consider  the 
cause  of  friendship ;  so  that  in  the  friendship  that  is  based 
on  the  useful,  repayment  should  be  made  according  to  the 
usefulness  accruing  from  the  favour  conferred,  and  in  the 
friendship  based  on  virtue  repayment  should  be  made  with 
regard  for  the  choice  or  disposition  of  the  giver,  since  this 
is  the  chief  requisite  of  virtue,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  viii.  13. 
And  likewise,  since  gratitude  regards  the  favour  inasmuch  as 
it  is  bestowed  gratis,  and  this  regards  the  disposition  of  the 
giver,  it  follows  again  that  repayment  of  a  favour  depends 
more  on  the  disposition  of  the  giver  than  on  the  effect. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Every  moral  act  depends  on  the  will. 
Hence  a  kindly  action,  in  so  far  as  it  is  praiseworthy  and  is 
deserving  of  gratitude,  consists  materially  in  the  thing  done, 
but  formally  and  chiefly  in  the  will.  Hence  Seneca  says 
(De  Benef.  i.) :  A  kindly  action  consists  not  in  deed  or  gift,  but 
in  the  disposition  of  the  giver  or  doer. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Gratitude  is  a  part  of  justice,  not  indeed  as 


55  THANKFULNESS  Q.  io6.Art.g 

a  species  is  part  of  a  genus,  but  by  a  kind  of  reduction  to  the 
genus  of  justice,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXX.).  Hence  it 
does  not  follow  that  we  shall  find  the  same  kind  of  debt  in 
both  virtues. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  God  alone  sees  man's  disposition  in  itself: 
but  in  so  far  as  it  is  shown  by  certain  signs,  man  also  can 
know  it.  It  is  thus  that  a  benefactor's  disposition  is  known 
by  the  way  in  which  he  does  the  kindly  action,  for  instance 
through  his  doing  it  joyfully  and  readily. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  the  repayment  of  gratitude  should  surpass 
the  favour  received  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  there  is  no  need  for  the  repay- 
ment of  gratitude  to  surpass  the  favour  received.  For  it  is 
not  possible  to  make  even  equal  repayment  to  some,  for 
instance,  to  one's  parents,  as  the  Philosopher  states 
(Ethic,  viii.  14).  Now  virtue  does  not  attempt  the  impos- 
sible. Therefore  gratitude  for  a  favour  does  not  tend  to 
something  yet  greater. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  If  one  person  repays  another  more  than 
he  has  received  by  his  favour,  by  that  very  fact  he  gives 
him  something  in  his  turn,  as  it  were.  But  the  latter  owes 
him  repayment  for  the  favour  which  in  his  turn  the  former 
has  conferred  on  him.  Therefore  he  that  first  conferred  a 
favour  will  be  bound  to  a  yet  greater  repayment,  and  so  on 
indefinitely.  Now  virtue  does  not  strive  at  the  indefinite, 
since  the  indefinite  removes  the  nature  of  good  (Metaph.  ii. 
text.  8).  Therefore  repayment  of  gratitude  should  not 
surpass  the  favour  received. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Justice  consists  in  equality.  But  more 
is  excess  of  equality.  Since  therefore  excess  is  sinful  in 
every  virtue,  it  seems  that  to  repay  more  than  the  favour 
received  is  sinful  and  opposed  to  justice. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  v.  5):  We 
should  repay  those  who  are  gracious  to  us,  by  being  gracious 


Q.  106.  Art.  6   THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  56 

to  them  in  return,  and  this  is  done  by  repaying  more  than 
we  have  received.  Therefore  gratitude  should  incline  to  do 
something  greater. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  5),  gratitude  regards  the 
favour  received  according  to  the  intention  of  the  benefactor; 
who  seems  to  be  deserving  of  praise,  chiefly  for  having  con- 
ferred the  favour  gratis  without  being  bound  to  do  so. 
Wherefore  the  beneficiary  is  under  a  moral  obligation  to 
bestow  something  gratis  in  return.  Now  he  does  not  seem 
to  bestow  something  gratis,  unless  he  exceeds  the  quantity 
of  the  favour  received :  because  so  long  as  he  repays  less  or 
an  equivalent,  he  would  seem  to  do  nothing  gratis,  but  only 
to  return  what  he  has  received.  Therefore  gratitude  always 
inclines,  as  far  as  possible,  to  pay  back  something  more. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  stated  above  (A.  3,  ad  5,  A.  5),  in  repaying 
favours  we  must  consider  the  disposition  rather  than  the 
deed.  Accordingly,  if  we  consider  the  effect  of  beneficence, 
which  a  son  receives  from  his  parents,  namely,  to  be  and  to 
live,  the  son  cannot  make  an  equal  repayment,  as  the 
Philosopher  states  (Ethic,  viii.  14).  But  if  we  consider  the 
will  of  the  giver  and  of  the  repayer,  then  it  is  possible  for 
the  son  to  pay  back  something  greater  to  his  father, 
as  Seneca  declares  (De  Benef.  hi.).  If,  however,  he  were 
unable  to  do  so,  the  will  to  pay  back  would  be  sufficient  for 
gratitude. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  debt  of  gratitude  flows  from  charity, 
which  the  more  it  is  paid  the  more  it  is  due,  according  to 
Rom.  xiii.  8,  Owe  no  man  anything,  but  to  love  one  another. 
Wherefore  it  is  not  unreasonable  if  the  obligation  of  grati- 
tude has  no  limit. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  in  justice,  which  is  a  cardinal  virtue,  we 
consider  equality  of  things,  so  in  gratitude  we  consider 
equality  of  wills.  For  while  on  the  one  hand  the  benefactor 
of  his  own  free-will  gave  something  he  was  not  bound  to 
give,  so  on  the  other  hand  the  beneficiary  repays  something 
over  and  above  what  he  has  received. 


QUESTION  CVII. 

OF    INGRATITUDE. 

(In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  ingratitude,  under  which  head  there 
are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  ingratitude  is  always 
a  sin  ?  (2)  Whether  ingratitude  is  a  special  sin  ?  (3)  Whether 
every  act  of  ingratitude  is  a  mortal  sin  ?  (4)  Whether  favours 
should  be  withdrawn  from  the  ungrateful  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  ingratitude  is  always  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  ingratitude  is  not  always  a  sin. 
For  Seneca  says  (De  Benef  iii.)  that  he  who  does  not  repay  a 
favour  is  ungrateful.  But  sometimes  it  is  impossible  to 
repay  a  favour  without  sinning,  for  instance  if  one  man  has 
helped  another  to  commit  a  sin.  Therefore,  since  it  is  not 
a  sin  to  refrain  from  sinning,  it  seems  that  ingratitude  is  not 
always  a  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Every  sin  is  in  the  power  of  the  person 
who  commits  it:  because,  according  to  Augustine  (De  Lib. 
Arb.  iii.:  Retract,  i.),  no  man  sins  in  what  he  cannot  avoid. 
Now  sometimes  it  is  not  in  the  power  of  the  sinner  to  avoid 
ingratitude,  for  instance  when  he  has  not  the  means  of 
repaying.  Again  forgetfulness  is  not  in  our  power,  and  yet 
Seneca  declares  (De  Benef.  iii.)  that  to  forget  a  kindness  is 
the  height  of  ingratitude.  Therefore  ingratitude  is  not  always 
a  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  There  would  seem  to  be  no  repayment  in 

57 


Q.  107.  Art.  i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  s8 

being  unwilling  to  owe  anything,  according  to  the  Apostle 
(Rom.  xiii.  8),  Owe  no  man  anything.  Yet  an  unwilling 
debtor  is  ungrateful,  as  Seneca  declares  (De  Bene/,  iv.). 
Therefore  ingratitude  is  not  always  a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Ingratitude  is  reckoned  among  other  sins 
(2  Tim.  iii.  2),  where  it  is  written:  Disobedient  to  parents, 
ungrateful,  wicked,  etc. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CVL,  A.  4,  ad  1,  A.  6) 
a  debt  of  gratitude  is  a  moral  debt  required  by  virtue.  Now 
a  thing  is  a  sin  from  the  fact  of  its  being  contrary  to  virtue. 
Wherefore  it  is  evident  that  every  ingratitude  is  a  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Gratitude  regards  a  favour  received:  and 
he  that  helps  another  to  commit  a  sin  does  him  not  a  favour 
but  an  injury:  and  so  no  thanks  are  due  to  him,  except  per- 
haps on  account  of  his  good  will,  supposing  him  to  have  been 
deceived,  and  to  have  thought  to  help  him  in  doing  good, 
whereas  he  helped  him  to  sin.  In  such  a  case  the  repay- 
ment due  to  him  is  not  that  he  should  be  helped  to  commit 
a  sin,  because  this  would  be  repaying  not  good  but  evil,  and 
this  is  contrary  to  gratitude. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  No  man  is  excused  from  ingratitude  through 
inability  to  repay,  for  the  very  reason  that  the  mere  will 
suffices  for  the  repayment  of  the  debt  of  gratitude,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  CVL,  A.  6,  ad  1). 

Forgetfulness  of  a  favour  received  amounts  to  ingratitude, 
not  indeed  the  forgetfulness  that  arises  from  a  natural  defect, 
that  is  not  subject  to  the  will,  but  that  which  arises  from 
negligence.  For,  as  Seneca  observes  {De  Bene/,  iii.),  when 
forgetfulness  of  favours  lays  hold  of  a  man,  he  has  apparently 
given  little  thought  to  their  repayment. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  debt  of  gratitude  flows  from  the  debt  of 
love,  and  from  the  latter  no  man  should  wish  to  be  free. 
Hence  that  anyone  should  owe  this  debt  unwillingly  seems 
to  arise  from  lack  of  love  for  his  benefactor. 


59  INGRATITUDE  Q.  107.  Art.  2 

Second  Article, 
whether  ingratitude  is  a  special  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  I.  It  seems  that  ingratitude  is  not  a  special  sin. 
For  whoever  sins  acts  against  God  his  sovereign  benefactor. 
But  this  pertains  to  ingratitude.  Therefore  ingratitude  is 
not  a  special  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  No  special  sin  is  contained  under  different 
kinds  of  sin.  But  one  can  be  ungrateful  by  committing 
different  kinds  of  sin,  for  instance  by  calumny,  theft,  or  some- 
thing similar  committed  against  a  benefactor.  Therefore 
ingratitude  is  not  a  special  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Seneca  writes  {De  Bene/,  iii.):  It  is  un- 
grateful to  take  no  notice  of  a  kindness,  it  is  ungrateful  not  to 
repay  one,  but  it  is  the  height  of  ingratitude  to  forget  it.  Now 
these  do  not  seem  to  belong  to  the  same  species  of  sin.  There- 
fore ingratitude  is  not  a  special  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Ingratitude  is  opposed  to  gratitude  or 
thankfulness,  which  is  a  special  virtue.  Therefore  it  is  a 
special  sin. 

I  answer  that,  Every  vice  is  denominated  from  a  deficiency 
of  virtue,  because  deficiency  is  more  opposed  to  virtue :  thus 
illiberality  is  more  opposed  to  liberality  than  prodigality  is. 
Now  a  vice  may  be  opposed  to  the  virtue  of  gratitude  by  way 
of  excess,  for  instance  if  one  were  to  show  gratitude  for 
things  for  which  gratitude  is  not  due,  or  sooner  than  it  is 
due,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CVL,  A.  4).  But  still  more  opposed 
to  gratitude  is  the  vice  denoting  deficiency  of  gratitude,  be- 
cause the  virtue  of  gratitude,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CVL,  A.  6), 
inclines  to  return  something  more.  Wherefore  ingratitude 
is  properly  denominated  from  being  a  deficiency  of  grati- 
tude. Now  every  deficiency  or  privation  takes  its  species 
from  the  opposite  habit :  for  blindness  and  deafness  differ 
according  to  the  difference  of  sight  and  hearing.  Therefore 
just  as  gratitude  or  thankfulness  is  one  special  virtue,  so  also 
is  ingratitude  one  special  sin. 


Q.  107.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  60 

It  has,  however,  various  degrees  corresponding  in  their 
order  to  the  things  required  for  gratitude.  The  first  of  these 
is  to  recognize  the  favour  received,  the  second  to  express 
one's  appreciation  and  thanks,  and  the  third  to  repay  the 
favour  at  a  suitable  place  and  time  according  to  one's 
means.  And  since  what  is  last  in  the  order  of  generation 
is  first  in  the  order  of  destruction,  it  follows  that  the  first 
degree  of  ingratitude  is  when  a  man  fails  to  repay  a  favour, 
the  second  when  he  declines  to  notice  and  indicate  that  he 
has  received  a  favour,  while  the  third  and  supreme  degree  is 
when  a  man  fails  to  recognize  the  reception  of  a  favour, 
whether  by  forgetting  it  or  in  any  other  way.  Moreover, 
since  opposite  affirmation  includes  negation,  it  follows  that 
it  belongs  to  the  first  degree  of  ingratitude  to  return  evil  for 
good,  to  the  second  to  find  fault  with  a  favour  received,  and 
to  the  third  to  esteem  kindness  as  though  it  were  un- 
kindness. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  In  every  sin  there  is  material  ingratitude 
to  God,  inasmuch  as  a  man  does  something  that  may 
pertain  to  ingratitude.  But  formal  ingratitude  is  when  a 
favour  is  actually  contemned,  and  this  is  a  special  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Nothing  hinders  the  formal  aspect  of  some 
special  sin  from  being  found  materially  in  several  kinds  of 
sin,  and  in  this  way  the  aspect  of  ingratitude  is  to  be  found 
in  many  kinds  of  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  These  three  are  not  different  species  but 
different  degrees  of  one  special  sin. 

Third  Article, 
whether  ingratitude  is  always  a  mortal  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  ingratitude  is  always  a  mortal 
sin.  For  one  ought  to  be  grateful  to  God  above  all.  But 
one  is  not  ungrateful  to  God  by  committing  a  venial  sin: 
else  every  man  would  be  guilty  of  ingratitude.  Therefore 
no  ingratitude  is  a  venial  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  A  sin  is  mortal  through  being  contrary 


61  INGRATITUDE  Q.  107.  Art.  3 

to  charity,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXIV.,  A.  12).  But  in- 
gratitude is  contrary  to  charity,  since  the  debt  of  gratitude 
proceeds  from  that  virtue,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CVL,  A.  1,  ad  3, 
A.  6,  ad  2).     Therefore  ingratitude  is  always  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Seneca  says  (De  Bene/,  ii.) :  Between  the 
giver  and  the  receiver  of  a  favour  there  is  this  law,  that  the 
former  should  forthwith  forget  having  given,  and  the  latter 
should  never  forget  having  received.  Now,  seemingly,  the 
reason  why  the  giver  should  forget  is  that  he  may  be  un- 
aware of  the  sin  of  the  recipient,  should  the  latter  prove 
ungrateful;  and  there  would  be  no  necessity  for  that  if 
ingratitude  were  a  slight  sin.  Therefore  ingratitude  is  always 
a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  4.  On  the  contrary,  No  one  should  be  put  in  the  way  of 
committing  a  mortal  sin.  Yet,  according  to  Seneca  {ibid.), 
sometimes  it  is  necessary  to  deceive  the  person  who  receives 
assistance,  in  order  that  he  may  receive  without  knowing  from 
whom  he  has  received.  But  this  would  seem  to  put  the 
recipient  in  the  way  of  ingratitude.  Therefore  ingratitude 
is  not  always  a  mortal  sin. 

/  answer  that,  As  appears  from  what  we  have  said  above 
(A.  2),  a  man  may  be  ungrateful  in  two  ways:  first,  by  mere 
omission,  for  instance  by  failing  to  recognize  the  favour 
received,  or  to  express  his  appreciation  of  it,  or  to  pay  some- 
thing in  return,  and  this  is  not  always  a  mortal  sin,  because, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  CVL,  A.  6),  the  debt  of  gratitude  requires 
a  man  to  make  a  liberal  return,  which,  however,  he  is  not 
bound  to  do;  wherefore  if  he  fail  to  do  so,  he  does  not  sin 
mortally.  It  is  nevertheless  a  venial  sin,  because  it  arises 
either  from  some  kind  of  negligence  or  from  some  disinclina- 
tion to  virtue  in  him.  And  yet  ingratitude  of  this  kind  may 
happen  to  be  a  mortal  sin,  by  reason  either  of  inward  con- 
tempt, or  of  the  kind  of  thing  withheld,  this  being  needful 
to  the  benefactor,  either  simply,  or  in  some  case  of  necessity. 

Secondly,  a  man  may  be  ungrateful,  because  he  not  only 
omits  to  pay  the  debt  of  gratitude,  but  does  the  contrary. 
This  again  is  sometimes  a  mortal  and  sometimes  a  venial 
sin,  according  to  the  kind  of  thing  that  is  done. 


Q.io7.Art.3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  62 

It  must  be  observed,  however,  that  when  ingratitude 
arises  from  a  mortal  sin,  it  has  the  perfect  character  of 
ingratitude,  and  when  it  arises  from  venial  sin,  it  has  the 
imperfect  character. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  By  committing  a  venial  sin  one  is  not  un- 
grateful to  God  to  the  extent  of  incurring  the  guilt  of  perfect 
ingratitude :  but  there  is  something  of  ingratitude  in  a  venial 
sin,  in  so  far  as  it  removes  a  virtuous  act  of  obedience  to  God. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  When  ingratitude  is  a  venial  sin  it  is  not 
contrary  to,  but  beside  charity:  since  it  does  not  destroy  the 
habit  of  charity,  but  excludes  some  act  thereof. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Seneca  also  says  (De  Benef.  vii.):  When  we 
say  that  a  man  after  conferring  a  favour  should  forget  about  it, 
it  is  a  mistake  to  suppose  that  we  mean  him  to  shake  off  the 
recollection  of  a  thing  so  very  praiseworthy.  When  we  say : 
He  must  not  remember  it,  we  mean  that  he  must  not  publish 
it  abroad  and  boast  about  it. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  He  that  is  unaware  of  a  favour  conferred 
on  him  is  not  ungrateful,  if  he  fails  to  repay  it,  provided  he 
be  prepared  to  do  so  if  he  knew.  It  is  nevertheless  com- 
mendable at  times  that  the  object  of  a  favour  should  remain 
in  ignorance  of  it,  both  in  order  to  avoid  vainglory,  as  when 
Blessed  Nicolas  threw  gold  into  a  house  secretly,  wishing  to 
avoid  popularity ;  and  because  the  kindness  is  all  the  greater 
through  the  benefactor  wishing  not  to  shame  the  person  on 
whom  he  is  conferring  the  favour. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  favours  should  be  withheld  from  the 

ungrateful  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  favours  should  be  withheld  from 
the  ungrateful.  For  it  is  written  (Wis.  xvi.  29) :  The  hope  of 
the  unthankful  shall  melt  away  as  the  winter's  ice.  But  this 
hope  would  not  melt  away  unless  favours  were  withheld  from 
him.  Therefore  favours  should  be  withheld  from  the  un- 
grateful. 


63  INGRATITUDE  Q.  107.  Art.  4 

Obj.  2.  Further,  No  one  should  afford  another  an  occasion 
of  committing  sin.  But  the  ungrateful  in  receiving  a  favour 
is  given  an  occasion  of  ingratitude.  Therefore  favours 
should  not  be  bestowed  on  the  ungrateful. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  By  what  things  a  man  sinneth,  by  the  same 
also  he  is  tormented  (Wis.  xi.  17).  Now  he  that  is  ungrateful 
when  he  receives  a  favour  sins  against  the  favour.  There- 
fore he  should  be  deprived  of  the  favour. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Luke  vi.  35)  that  the 
Highest  .  .  .  is  kind  to  the  unthankful,  and  to  the  evil.  Now 
we  should  prove  ourselves  His  children  by  imitating  Him 
{ibid.  36).  Therefore  we  should  not  withhold  favours  from 
the  ungrateful. 

i"  answer  that,  There  are  two  points  to  be  considered  with 
regard  to  an  ungrateful  person.  The  first  is  what  he  de- 
serves to  suffer,  and  thus  it  is  certain  that  he  deserves  to  be 
deprived  of  our  favour.  The  second  is,  what  ought  his  bene- 
factor to  do  ?  For  in  the  first  place  he  should  not  easily 
judge  him  to  be  ungrateful,  since,  as  Seneca  remarks  (De 
Bene/,  iii.),  a  man  is  often  grateful  although  he  repays  not, 
because  perhaps  he  has  not  the  means  or  the  opportunity  of 
repaying.  Secondly,  he  should  be  inclined  to  turn  his  un- 
gratefulness into  gratitude,  and  if  he  does  not  achieve  this 
by  being  kind  to  him  once,  he  may  by  being  so  a  second  time. 
If,  however,  the  more  he  repeats  his  favours,  the  more 
ungrateful  and  evil  the  other  becomes,  he  should  cease  from 
bestowing  his  favours  upon  him. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  passage  quoted  speaks  of  what  the 
ungrateful  man  deserves  to  suffer. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  He  that  bestows  a  favour  on  an  ungrateful 
person  affords  him  an  occasion  not  of  sin  but  of  gratitude  and 
love.  And  if  the  recipient  takes  therefrom  an  occasion  of 
ingratitude,  this  is  not  to  be  imputed  to  the  bestower. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  He  that  bestows  a  favour  must  not  at  once 
act  the  part  of  a  punisher  of  ingratitude,  but  rather  that  of  a 
kindly  physician,  by  healing  the  ingratitude  with  repeated 
favours. 


QUESTION  CVIII. 

OF  VENGEANCE. 
(In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  vengeance,  under  which  head  there 
are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  vengeance  is  law- 
ful ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  a  special  virtue  ?  (3)  Of  the  manner 
of  taking  vengeance:  (4)  On  whom  should  vengeance  be 
taken  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  vengeance  is  lawful  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  vengeance  is  not  lawful.  For 
whoever  usurps  what  is  God's  sins.  But  vengeance  belongs 
to  God,  for  it  is  written  (Deut.  xxxii.  35,  and  Rom.  xii.  19) : 
Revenge  to  Me,  and  I  will  repay.  Therefore  all  vengeance  is 
unlawful. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  He  that  takes  vengeance  on  a  man 
does  not  bear  with  him.  But  we  ought  to  bear  with  the 
wicked,  for  a  gloss  on  Cant.  ii.  2,  As  the  lily  among  the  thorns, 
says :  He  is  not  a  good  man  that  cannot  bear  with  a  wicked  one. 
Therefore  we  should  not  take  vengeance  on  the  wicked. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Vengeance  is  taken  by  inflicting  punish- 
ment, which  is  the  cause  of  servile  fear.  But  the  New  Law  is 
not  a  law  of  fear,  but  of  love,  as  Augustine  states  (Contra 
Adamant,  xvii.).  Therefore  at  least  in  the  New  Testament 
all  vengeance  is  unlawful. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  A  man  is  said  to  avenge  himself  when  he 
takes  revenge  for  wrongs  inflicted  on  himself.  But,  seem- 
ingly, it  is  unlawful  even  for  a  judge  to  punish  those  who  have 

64 


65  VENGEANCE  Q.  108.  Art.  i 

wronged  him :  for  Chrysostom*  says :  Let  us  learn  after  Christ's 
example  to  bear  our  own  wrongs  with  magnanimity,  yet  not  to 
suffer  God's  wrongs,  not  even  by  listening  to  them.  Therefore 
vengeance  seems  to  be  unlawful. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  The  sin  of  a  multitude  is  more  harmful 
than  the  sin  of  only  one :  for  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  xxvi.  5-7) : 
Of  three  things  my  heart  hath  been  afraid  .  .  .  the  accusation 
of  a  city,  and  the  gathering  together  of  the  people,  and  a  false 
calumny.  But  vengeance  should  not  be  taken  on  the  sin 
of  a  multitude,  for  a  gloss  on  Matth.  xiii.  29,  30,  Lest  per- 
haps .  .  .  you  root  up  the  wheat  .  .  .  suffer  both  to  grow,  says 
that  a  multitude  should  not  be  excommunicated,  nor  should  the 
sovereign.     Neither  therefore  is  any  other  vengeance  lawful. 

On  the  contrary,  We  should  look  to  God  for  nothing  save 
what  is  good  and  lawful.  But  we  are  to  look  to  God  for 
vengeance  on  His  enemies :  for  it  is  written  (Luke  xviii.  7) : 
Will  not  God  revenge  His  elect  who  cry  to  Him  day  and  night  ? 
as  if  to  say:  He  will  indeed.  Therefore  vengeance  is  not 
essentially  evil  and  unlawful. 

/  answer  that,  Vengeance  consists  in  the  infliction  of  a 
penal  evil  on  one  who  has  sinned.  Accordingly,  in  the 
matter  of  vengeance,  we  must  consider  the  mind  of  the 
avenger.  For  if  his  intention  is  directed  chiefly  to  the  evil 
of  the  person  on  whom  he  takes  vengeance,  and  rests  there, 
then  his  vengeance  is  altogether  unlawful:  because  to  take 
pleasure  in  another's  evil  belongs  to  hatred,  which  is  contrary 
co  the  charity  whereby  we  are  bound  to  love  all  men.  Nor 
is  it  an  excuse  that  he  intends  the  evil  of  one  who  has  unjustly 
inflicted  evil  on  him,  as  neither  is  a  man  excused  for  hating 
one  that  hates  him :  for  a  man  may  not  sin  against  another 
just  because  the  latter  has  already  sinned  against  him,  since 
this  is  to  be  overcome  b\'  evil,  Which  was  forbidden  by  the 
Apostle,  who  says  (Rom.  xii.  21) :  Be  not  overcome  by  evil,  but 
overcome  evil  by  good. 

If,  however,  the  avenger's  intention  be  directed  chiefly  to 
some  good,  to  be  obtained  by  means  of  the  punishment  of 

*  Cf.  Opus  Imperfectum,  Horn.  v.  in  Matth.  falsely  ascribed  to 
S.  Chrysostom. 

11.  ii.  4  5 


Q.  108.  Art.  i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  66 

the  person  who  has  sinned  (for  instance  that  the  sinner  may 
amend,  or  at  least  that  he  may  be  restrained  and  others 
be  not  disturbed,  that  justice  may  be  upheld,  and  God 
honoured),  then  vengeance  maybe  lawful,  provided  other  due 
circumstances  be  observed. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  He  who  takes  vengeance  on  the  wicked  in 
keeping  with  his  rank  and  position  does  not  usurp  what 
belongs  to  God,  but  makes  use  of  the  power  granted  him  by 
God.  For  it  is  written  (Rom.  xiii.  4)  of  the  earthly  prince 
that  he  is  God's  minister,  an  avenger  to  execute  wrath  upon 
him  that  doeth  evil.  If,  however,  a  man  takes  vengeance 
outside  the  order  of  divine  appointment,  he  usurps  what 
is  God's  and  therefore  sins. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  good  bear  with  the  wicked  by  enduring 
patiently,  and  in  due  manner,  the  wrongs  they  themselves 
receive  from  them :  but  they  do  not  bear  with  them  so  as  to 
endure  the  wrongs  they  inflict  on  God  and  their  neighbour. 
For  Chrysostom*  says :  It  is  praiseworthy  to  be  patient  under 
our  own  wrongs,  but  to  overlook  God's  wrongs  is  most  wicked. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  law  of  the  Gospel  is  the  law  of  love,  and 
therefore  those  who  do  good  out  of  love,  and  who  alone 
properly  belong  to  the  Gospel,  ought  not  to  be  terrorized 
by  means  of  punishment,  but  only  those  who  are  not  moved 
by  love  to  do  good,  and  who,  though  they  belong  to  the 
Church  outwardly,  do  not  belong  to  it  in  merit. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Sometimes  a  wrong  done  to  a  person 
reflects  on  God  and  the  Church:  and  then  it  is  the  duty  of 
that  person  to  avenge  the  wrong.  For  example,  Elias  made 
fire  descend  on  those  who  were  come  to  seize  him  (4  Kings  i.) ; 
likewise  Eliseus  cursed  the  boys  that  mocked  him  (4  Kings  ii.) ; 
and  Pope  Sylverius  excommunicated  those  who  sent  him 
into  exile  (XXIII.,  Q.  iv.,  Cap.  Guilisarius).  But  in  so  far 
as  the  wrong  inflicted  on  a  man  affects  his  person,  he  should 
bear  it  patiently  if  this  be  expedient.  For  these  precepts 
of  patience  are  to  be  understood  as  referring  to  preparedness 
of  the  mind,  as  Augustine  states  (De  Serm.  Dom.  in  Monte  i.). 

Reply  Obj.  5.  When  the  whole  multitude  sins,  vengeance 

*  Cf.  Obj.  4  and  footnote. 


6y  VENGEANCE  Q.  108.  Art.  i 

must  be  taken  on  them,  either  in  respect  of  the  whole 
multitude — thus  the  Egyptians  were  drowned  in  the  Red 
Sea  while  they  were  pursuing  the  children  of  Israel  (Exod. 
xiv.),  and  the  people  of  Sodom  were  entirely  destroyed 
(Gen.  xix.) — or  as  regards  part  of  the  multitude,  as  may 
be  seen  in  the  punishment  of  those  who  worshipped  the  calf. 

Sometimes,  however,  if  there  is  hope  of  many  making 
amends,  the  severity  of  vengeance  should  be  brought  to 
bear  on  a  few  of  the  principals,  whose  punishment  nils  the 
rest  with  fear;  thus  the  Lord  (Num.  xxv.)  commanded 
the  princes  of  the  people  to  be  hanged  for  the  sin  of  the 
multitude. 

On  the  other  hand,  if  it  is  not  the  whole  but  only  a  part  of 
the  multitude  that  has  sinned,  then  if  the  guilty  can  be 
separated  from  the  innocent,  vengeance  should  be  wrought  on 
them:  provided,  however,  that  this  can  be  done  without 
scandal  to  others;  else  the  multitude  should  be  spared  and 
severity  forgone.  The  same  applies  to  the  sovereign,  whom 
the  multitude  follow.  For  his  sin  should  be  borne  with,  if 
it  cannot  be  punished  without  scandal  to  the  multitude: 
unless  indeed  his  sin  were  such,  that  it  would  do  more  harm 
to  the  multitude,  either  spirituahy  or  temporally,  than  would 
the  scandal  that  was  feared  to  arise  from  his  punishment. 

Second  Article, 
whether  vengeance  is  a  special  virtue? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  vengeance  is  not  a  special 
and  distinct  virtue.  For  just  as  the  good  are  rewarded  for 
their  good  deeds,  so  are  the  wicked  punished  for  their  evil 
deeds.  Now  the  rewarding  of  the  good  does  not  belong  to 
a  special  virtue,  but  is  an  act  of  commutative  justice. 
Therefore  in  the  same  way  vengeance  should  not  be  ac- 
counted a  special  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  There  is  no  need  to  appoint  a  special 
virtue  for  an  act  to  which  a  man  is  sufficiently  disposed  by 
the  other  virtues.     Now  man  is  sufficiently  disposed  by  the 


Q.io8.Art.2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  68 

virtues  of  fortitude  or  zeal  to  avenge  evil.  Therefore 
vengeance  should  not  be  reckoned  a  special  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  There  is  a  special  vice  opposed  to  every 
special  virtue.  But  seemingly  no  special  vice  is  opposed 
to  vengeance.     Therefore  it  is  not  a  special  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  reckons  it  a  part 
of  justice. 

/  answer  that,  As  the  Philosopher  states  (Ethic,  ii.  i),  apti- 
tude to  virtue  is  in  us  by  nature,  but  the  complement  of 
virtue  is  in  us  through  habituation  or  some  other  cause. 
Hence  it  is  evident  that  virtues  perfect  us  so  that  we  follow 
in  due  manner  our  natural  inclinations,  which  belong  to  the 
natural  right.  Wherefore  to  every  definite  natural  inclina- 
tion there  corresponds  a  special  virtue.  Now  there  is  a 
special  inclination  of  nature  to  remove  harm,  for  which 
reason  animals  have  the  irascible  power  distinct  from  the 
concupiscible.  Man  resists  harm  by  defending  himself 
against  wrongs,  lest  they  be  inflicted  on  him,  or  he  avenges 
those  which  have  already  been  inflicted  on  him,  with  the 
intention,  not  of  harming,  but  of  removing  the  harm  done. 
And  this  belongs  to  vengeance,  for  Tully  says  (loc.  cit.) 
that  by  vengeance  we  resist  force,  or  wrong,  and  in  general 
whatever  is  obscure*  (i.e.  derogatory),  either  by  self-defence 
or  by  avenging  it.     Therefore  vengeance  is  a  special  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Just  as  repayment  of  a  legal  debt  belongs  to 
commutative  justice,  and  as  repayment  of  a  moral  debt, 
arising  from  the  bestowal  of  a  particular  favour,  belongs  to 
the  virtue  of  gratitude,  so  too  the  punishment  of  sins, 
so  far  as  it  is  the  concern  of  public  justice,  is  an  act  of  com- 
mutative justice;  while  so  far  as  it  is  concerned  in  defending 
the  rights  of  the  individual  by  whom  a  wrong  is  resisted,  it 
belongs  to  the  virtue  of  revenge. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Fortitude  disposes  to  vengeance  by  re- 
moving an  obstacle  thereto,  namely,  fear  of  an  imminent 
danger.  Zeal,  as  denoting  the  fervour  of  love,  signifies  the 
primary  root  of  vengeance,  in  so  far  as  a  man  avenges  the 

*  Obscurum.  Cicero  wrote  obfuturum:  but  the  sense  is  the  same  as 
S.  Thomas  gives  in  the  parenthesis. 


69  VENGEANCE  Q.  108.  Art.  3 

wrong  done  to  God  and  his  neighbour,  because  charity  makes 
him  regard  them  as  his  own.  Now  every  act  of  virtue 
proceeds  from  charity  as  its  root,  since,  according  to  Gregory 
(Horn,  xxvii.  in  Ev.),  there  are  no  green  leaves  on  the  bough 
of  good  works,  unless  charity  be  the  root. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Two  vices  are  opposed  to  vengeance:  one 
by  way  of  excess,  namely,  the  sin  of  cruelty  or  brutality, 
which  exceeds  the  measure  in  punishing :  while  the  other  is 
a  vice  by  way  of  deficiency  and  consists  in  being  remiss  in 
punishing,  wherefore  it  is  written  (Prov.  xiii.  24) :  He  that 
spareth  the  rod  hateth  his  sow.  But  the  virtue  of  vengeance 
consists  in  observing  the  due  measure  of  vengeance  with 
regard  to  all  the  circumstances. 

Third  Article. 

whether  vengeance  should  be  wrought  by  means  of 
punishments  customary  among  men  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  vengeance  should  not  be 
wrought  by  means  of  punishments  customary  among  men. 
For  to  put  a  man  to  death  is  to  uproot  him.  But  Our 
Lord  forbade  (Matth.  xiii.  29)  the  uprooting  of  the  cockle, 
whereby  the  children  of  the  wicked  one  are  signified.  There- 
fore sinners  should  not  be  put  to  death. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  All  who  sin  mortally  seem  to  be  deserv- 
ing of  the  same  punishment.  Therefore  if  some  who  sin 
mortally  are  punished  with  death,  it  seems  that  all  such 
persons  should  be  punished  with  death :  and  this  is  evidently 
false. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  To  punish  a  man  publicly  for  his  sin 
seems  to  publish  his  sin:  and  this  would  seem  to  have  a 
harmful  effect  on  the  multitude,  since  the  example  of  sin  is 
taken  by  them  as  an  occasion  for  sin.  Therefore  it  seems 
that  the  punishment  of  death  should  not  be  inflicted  for  a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  These  punishments  are  fixed  by  the  divine 
law  as  appears   from   what   we  have   said    above    (I. -II., 

Q-  cv.,  A.  2). 


Q.  108.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  70 

/  answer  that,  Vengeance  is  lawful  and  virtuous  so  far  as  it 
tends  to  the  prevention  of  evil.  Now  some  who  are  not 
influenced  by  motive  of  virtue  are  prevented  from  commit- 
ting sin,  through  fear  of  losing  those  things  which  they 
love  more  than  those  they  obtain  by  sinning,  else  fear  would 
be  no  restraint  to  sin.  Consequently  vengeance  for  sin 
should  be  taken  by  depriving  a  man  of  what  he  loves  most. 
Now  the  things  which  man  loves  most  are  life,  bodily  safety, 
his  own  freedom,  and  external  goods  such  as  riches,  his 
country  and  his  good  name.  Wherefore,  according  to 
Augustine's  reckoning  (De  Civ.  Dei  xxi.),  Tully  writes  thai 
the  laws  recognize  eight  kinds  of  punishment :  namely,  death, 
whereby  man  is  deprived  of  life;  stripes,  retaliation,  or  the 
loss  of  eye  for  eye,  whereby  man  forfeits  his  bodily  safet}'; 
slavery,  and  imprisonment,  whereby  he  is  deprived  of  free- 
dom ;  exile,  whereby  he  is  banished  from  his  country ;  fines, 
whereby  he  is  mulcted  in  his  riches ;  ignominy,  whereby  he 
loses  his  good  name. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Our  Lord  forbids  the  uprooting  of  the 
cockle,  when  there  is  fear  lest  the  wheat  be  uprooted  to- 
gether with  it.  But  sometimes  the  wicked  can  be  uprooted 
by  death,  not  only  without  danger,  but  even  with  great 
profit,  to  the  good.  Wherefore  in  such  a  case  the  punish- 
ment of  death  may  be  inflicted  on  sinners. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  All  who  sin  mortally  are  deserving  of  eternal 
death,  as  regards  future  retribution,  which  is  in  accordance 
with  the  truth  of  the  divine  judgment.  But  the  punish- 
ments of  this  life  are  more  of  a  medicinal  character ;  where- 
fore the  punishment  of  death  is  inflicted  on  those  sins  alone 
which  conduce  to  the  grave  undoing  of  others. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  very  fact  that  the  punishment,  whether 
of  death  or  of  any  kind  that  is  fearsome  to  man,  is  made 
known  at  the  same  time  as  the  sin,  makes  man's  will  averse 
to  sin:  because  the  fear  of  punishment  is  greater  than  the 
enticement  of  the  example  of  sin. 


71  VENGEANCE  Q.  108.  Art.  4 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  vengeance  should  be  taken  on  those  who 
have  sinned  involuntarily  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  vengeance  should  be  taken 
on  those  who  have  sinned  involuntarily.  For  the  will  of 
one  man  does  not  follow  from  the  will  of  another.  Yet  one 
man  is  punished  for  another,  according  to  Exod.  xx.  5, 
I  am  .  .  .  God  .  .  .  jealous,  visiting  the  iniquity  of  the 
fathers  upon  the  children,  unto  the  third  and  fourth  generation. 
Thus  for  the  sin  of  Cham,  his  son  Chanaan  was  cursed 
(Gen.  ix.  25),  and  for  the  sin  of  Giezi,  his  descendants  were 
struck  with  leprosy  (4  Kings  v.).  Again  the  blood  of 
Christ  lays  the  descendants  of  the  Jews  under  the  ban  of 
punishment,  for  they  said  (Matth.  xxvii.  25)  :  His  blood  be 
upon  us  and  upon  our  children.  Moreover,  we  read  (Josue  vii.) 
that  the  people  of  Israel  were  delivered  into  the  hands  of  their 
enemies  for  the  sin  of  Achan,  and  that  the  same  people  were 
overthrown  by  the  Philistines  on  account  of  the  sin  of  the 
sons  of  Heli  (1  Kings  iv.).  Therefore  a  person  is  to  be 
punished  without  having  deserved  it  voluntarily. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Nothing  is  voluntary  except  what  is  in  a 
man's  power.  But  sometimes  a  man  is  punished  for  what 
is  not  in  his  power;  thus  a  man  is  removed  from  the 
administration  of  the  Church  on  account  of  being  infected 
with  leprosy;  and  a  Church  ceases  to  be  an  episcopal  see  on 
account  of  the  depravity  or  evil  deeds  of  the  people.  There- 
fore vengeance  is  taken  not  only  for  voluntary  sins. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Ignorance  makes  an  act  involuntary. 
Now  vengeance  is  sometimes  taken  on  the  ignorant.  Thus 
the  children  of  the  people  of  Sodom,  though  they  were  in 
invincible  ignorance,  perished  with  their  parents  (Gen.  xix.). 
Again,  for  the  sin  of  Dathan  and  Abiron  their  children  were 
swallowed  up  together  with  them  (Num.  xvi.).  Moreover, 
dumb  animals,  which  are  devoid  of  reason,  were  commanded 
to  be  slain  on  account  of  the  sin  of  the  Amalekites  (1  Kings 


Q.  108.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  72 

xv.).  Therefore  vengeance  is  sometimes  taken  on  those 
who  have  deserved  it  involuntarily. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Compulsion  is  most  opposed  to  volun- 
tariness. But  a  man  does  not  escape  the  debt  of  punish- 
ment through  being  compelled  by  fear  to  commit  a  sin. 
Therefore  vengeance  is  sometimes  taken  on  those  who  have 
deserved  it  involuntarily. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  Ambrose  says  on  Luke  v.  that  the  ship  in 
which  Judas  was,  was  in  distress  ;  wherefore  Peter,  who  was 
calm  in  the  security  of  his  own  merits,  was  in  distress  about 
those  of  others.  But  Peter  did  not  will  the  sin  of  Judas. 
Therefore  a  person  is  sometimes  punished  without  having 
voluntarily  deserved  it. 

On  the  contrary,  Punishment  is  due  to  sin.  But  every 
sin  is  voluntary  according  to  Augustine  (De  Lib.  Arb.  hi.: 
Retract,  i.).  Therefore  vengeance  should  be  taken  only  on 
those  who  have  deserved  it  voluntarily. 

/  answer  that,  Punishment  may  be  considered  in  two  ways. 
First,  under  the  aspect  of  punishment,  and  in  this  way 
punishment  is  not  due  save  for  sin,  because  by  means  of 
punishment  the  equality  of  justice  is  restored,  in  so  far  as  he 
who  by  sinning  has  exceeded  in  following  his  own  will 
suffers  something  that  is  contrary  to  his  will.  Wherefore, 
since  every  sin  is  voluntary,  not  excluding  original  sin,  as 
stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXXXI.,  A.  1),  it  follows  that  no  one  is 
punished  in  this  way,  except  for  something  done  voluntarily. 
Secondly,  punishment  may  be  considered  as  a  medicine,  not 
only  healing  the  past  sin,  but  also  preserving  from  future 
sin,  or  conducing  to  some  good,  and  in  this  way  a  person  is 
sometimes  punished  without  any  fault  of  his  own,  yet  not 
without  cause. 

It  must,  however,  be  observed  that  a  medicine  never 
removes  a  greater  good  in  order  to  promote  a  lesser;  thus  the 
medicine  of  the  body  never  blinds  the  eye,  in  order  to  repair 
the  heel:  yet  sometimes  it  is  harmful  in  lesser  things  that 
it  may  be  helpful  in  things  of  greater  consequence.  And 
since  spiritual  goods  are  of  the  greatest  consequence,  while 
temporal  goods  are  least  important,  sometimes  a  person  is 


73  VENGEANCE  Q.  108.  Art.  4 

punished  in  his  temporal  goods  without  any  fault  of  his  own. 
Such  are  many  of  the  punishments  inflicted  by  God  in  this 
present  life  for  our  humiliation  or  probation.  But  no  one 
is  punished  in  spiritual  goods  without  any  fault  on  his  part, 
neither  in  this  nor  in  the  future  life,  because  in  the  latter 
punishment  is  not  medicinal,  but  a  result  of  spiritual  con- 
demnation. 

Reply  Obj.  I.  A  man  is  never  condemned  to  a  spiritual 
punishment  for  another  man's  sin,  because  spiritual  punish- 
ment affects  the  soul,  in  respect  of  which  each  man  is  master 
of  himself.  But  sometimes  a  man  is  condemned  to  punish- 
ment in  temporal  matters  for  the  sin  of  another,  and  this 
for  three  reasons.  First,  because  one  man  may  be  the 
temporal  goods  of  another,  and  so  he  may  be  punished  in 
punishment  of  the  latter:  thus  children,  as  to  the  body, 
are  a  belonging  of  their  father,  and  slaves  are  a  possession 
of  their  master.  Secondly,  when  one  person's  sin  is  trans- 
mitted to  another,  either  by  imitation,  as  children  copy  the 
sins  of  their  parents,  and  slaves  the  sins  of  their  masters,  so  as 
to  sin  with  greater  daring ;  or  by  way  of  merit,  as  the  sinful 
subjects  merit  a  sinful  superior,  according  to  Job  xxxiv.  30, 
Who  maketh  a  man  that  is  a  hypocrite  to  reign  for  the  sins  of 
the  people  ?  Hence  the  people  of  Israel  were  punished  for 
David's  sin  in  numbering  the  people  (2  Kings  xxiv.).  This 
may  also  happen  through  some  kind  of  consent  or  conni- 
vance: thus  sometimes  even  the  good  are  punished  in  tem- 
poral matters  together  with  the  wicked,  for  not  having  con- 
demned their  sins,  as  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  ix.). 
Thirdly,  in  order  to  mark  the  unity  of  human  fellowship, 
whereby  one  man  is  bound  to  be  solicitous  for  another,  lest 
he  sin;  and  in  order  to  inculcate  horror  of  sin,  seeing  that  the 
punishment  of  one  affects  all,  as  though  all  were  one  body, 
as  Augustine  says  in  speaking  of  the  sin  of  Achan  (QQ.  sup. 
Josue  viii.).  The  saying  of  the  Lord,  Visiting  the  iniquity 
of  the  fathers  upon  the  children  unto  the  third  and  fourth 
generation,  seems  to  belong  to  mercy  rather  than  to  severity, 
since  He  does  not  take  vengeance  forthwith,  but  waits  for 
some  future  time,  in  order  that  the  descendants  at  least 


Q.io8.Art.4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  74 

may  mend  their  ways;  yet  should  the  wickedness  of  the 
descendants  increase,  it  becomes  almost  necessary  to  take 
vengeance  on  them. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  Augustine  states  (loc.  cit.),  human  judg- 
ment should  conform  to  the  divine  judgment,  when  this  is 
manifest,  and  God  condemns  men  spiritually  for  their  own 
sins.  But  human  judgment  cannot  be  conformed  to  God's 
hidden  judgments,  whereby  He  punishes  certain  persons 
in  temporal  matters  without  any  fault  of  theirs,  since  man 
is  unable  to  grasp  the  reasons  of  these  judgments,  so  as  to 
know  what  is  expedient  for  each  individual.  Wherefore 
according  to  human  judgment  a  man  should  never  be  con- 
demned without  fault  of  his  own  to  an  inflictive  punish- 
ment, such  as  death,  mutilation  or  flogging.  But  a  man 
may  be  condemned,  even  according  to  human  judgment,  to 
a  punishment  of  forfeiture,  even  without  any  fault  on  his 
part,  but  not  without  cause:  and  this  in  three  ways. 

First,  through  a  person  becoming,  without  any  fault  of  his, 
disqualified  for  having  or  acquiring  a  certain  good :  thus  for 
being  infected  with  leprosy  a  man  is  removed  from  the 
administration  of  the  Church:  and  for  bigamy,  or  through 
pronouncing  a  death  sentence  a  man  is  hindered  from  re- 
ceiving sacred  orders. 

Secondly,  because  the  particular  good  that  he  forfeits 
is  not  his  own  but  common  property :  thus  that  an  episcopal 
see  be  attached  to  a  certain  church  belongs  to  the  good 
of  the  whole  city,  and  not  only  to  the  good  of  the  clerics. 

Thirdly,  because  the  good  of  one  person  may  depend  on 
the  good  of  another :  thus  in  the  crime  of  high  treason  a  son 
loses  his  inheritance  through  the  sin  of  his  parent. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  By  the  judgment  of  God  children  are 
punished  in  temporal  matters  together  with  their  parents, 
both  because  they  are  a  possession  of  their  parents,  so  that 
their  parents  are  punished  also  in  their  person,  and  because 
this  is  for  their  good  lest,  should  they  be  spared,  they  might 
imitate  the  sins  of  their  parents,  and  thus  deserve  to  be 
punished  still  more  severely. 

Vengeance  is  wrought  on   dumb  animals  and  any  other 


75  VENGEANCE  Q.  108.  Art.  4 

irrational  creatures,  because  in  this  way  their  owners  are 
punished;  and  also  in  horror  of  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  An  act  done  through  compulsion  of  fear  is 
not  involuntary  simply,  but  has  an  admixture  of  voluntari- 
ness, as  stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  VI.,  AA.  5,  6). 

Reply  Obj.  5.  The  other  apostles  were  distressed  about 
the  sin  of  Judas,  in  the  same  way  as  the  multitude  is 
punished  for  the  sin  of  one,  in  commendation  of  unity,  as 
stated  above  (Reply  Obj.  1,  2). 


QUESTION  CIX. 

OF  TRUTH. 
(In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  truth  and  the  vices  opposed  thereto. 
Concerning  truth  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether 
truth  is  a  virtue  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  a  special  virtue  ?  (3) 
Whether  it  is  a  part  of  justice  ?  (4)  Whether  it  inclines  to 
that  which  is  less  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  truth  is  a  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  truth  is  not  a  virtue.  For  the 
first  of  virtues  is  faith,  whose  object  is  truth.  Since  then 
the  object  precedes  the  habit  and  the  act,  it  seems  that  truth 
is  not  a  virtue,  but  something  prior  to  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  According  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  7), 
it  belongs  to  truth  that  a  man  should  state  things  concerning 
himself  to  be  neither  more  nor  less  than  they  are.  But  this 
is  not  always  praiseworthy — neither  in  good  things,  since 
according  to  Prov.  xxvii.  2,  Let  another  praise  thee,  and  not 
thy  own  mouth — nor  even  in  evil  things,  because  it  is  written 
in  condemnation  of  certain  people  (Isa.  iii.  9) :  They  have 
proclaimed  abroad  their  sin  as  Sodom,  and  they  have  not  hid 
it.     Therefore  truth  is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.   3.  Further,  Every  virtue  is  either  theological,   or 
intellectual,  or  moral.     Now  truth  is  not  a  theological  virtue, 
because  its  object  is  not  God  but  temporal  things.     For 
Tully  says  (De  Jnv.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  by  truth  we  faithfully  repre- 
sent things  as  thev  are,  were,  or  will  be.    Likewise  it  is  not  one 

76 


77  TRUTH  Q.  109.  Art.  i 

of  the  intellectual  virtues,  but  their  end.  Nor  again  is  it  a 
moral  virtue,  since  it  is  not  a  mean  between  excess  and 
deficiency,  for  the  more  one  tells  the  truth,  the  better  it  is. 
Therefore  truth  is  not  a  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  both  in  the  Second  and 
in  the  Fourth  Book  of  Ethics  places  truth  among  the  other 
virtues. 

/  answer  that,  Truth  can  be  taken  in  two  ways.  First,  for 
that  by  reason  of  which  a  thing  is  said  to  be  true,  and  thus 
truth  is  not  a  virtue,  but  the  object  or  end  of  a  virtue: 
because,  taken  in  this  way,  truth  is  not  a  habit,  which  is 
the  genus  containing  virtue,  but  a  certain  equality  between 
the  understanding  or  sign  and  the  thing  understood  or  signi- 
fied, or  again  between  a  thing  and  its  rule,  as  stated  in  the 
First  Part  (Q.  XVI.,  A.  1:  Q.  XXL,  A.  2).  Secondly,  truth 
may  stand  for  that  by  which  a  person  says  what  is  true,  in 
which  sense  one  is  said  to  be  truthful.  This  truth  or  truth- 
fulness must  needs  be  a  virtue,  because  to  say  what  is  true 
is  a  good  act :  and  virtue  is  that  which  makes  its  subject  good, 
and  renders  his  action  good. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  argument  takes  truth  in  the  first  sense. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  To  state  that  which  concerns  oneself,  in  so 
far  as  it  is  a  statement  of  what  is  true,  is  good  generically. 
Yet  this  does  not  suffice  for  it  to  be  an  act  of  virtue,  since  it 
is  requisite  for  that  purpose  that  it  should  also  be  clothed 
with  the  due  circumstances,  and  if  these  be  not  observed, 
the  act  will  be  sinful.  Accordingly  it  is  sinful  to  praise  one- 
self without  due  cause  even  for  that  which  is  true :  and  it  is 
also  sinful  to  publish  one's  sin,  by  praising  oneself  on  that 
account,  or  in  any  way  proclaiming  it  uselessly. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  A  person  who.  says  what  is  true,  utters 
certain  signs  which  are  in  conformity  with  things ;  and  such 
signs  are  either  words,  or  external  actions,  or  any  external 
thing.  Now' these  external  things  are  the  subject-matter 
of  the  moral  virtues  alone,  for  the  latter  are  concerned 
with  the  use  of  the  external  members,  in  so  far  as  this  use 
is  put  into  effect  at  the  command  of  the  will.  Wherefore 
truth  is  neither  a  theological,  nor  an  intellectual,  but  a  moral 


Q.  109.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  78 

virtue.  And  it  is  a  mean  between  excess  and  deficiency 
in  two  ways.  First,  on  the  part  of  the  object,  secondly,  on 
the  part  of  the  act.  On  the  part  of  the  object,  because  the 
true  essentially  denotes  a  kind  of  equality,  and  equal  is  a 
mean  between  more  and  less.  Hence  for  the  very  reason 
that  a  man  says  what  is  true  about  himself,  he  observes  the 
mean  between  one  that  says  more  than  the  truth  about 
himself,  and  one  that  says  less  than  the  truth.  On  the  part 
of  the  act,  to  observe  the  mean  is  to  tell  the  truth,  when  one 
ought,  and  as  one  ought.  Excess  consists  in  making  known 
one's  own  affairs  out  of  season,  and  deficiency  in  hiding 
them  when  one  ought  to  make  them  known. 

Second  Article, 
whether  truth  is  a  special  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  I.  It  seems  that  truth  is  not  a  special  virtue. 
For  the  true  and  the  good  are  convertible.  Now  goodness 
is  not  a  special  virtue,  in  fact  every  virtue  is  goodness, 
because  it  makes  its  subject  good.  Therefore  truth  is  not  a 
special  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  To  make  known  what  belongs  to  oneself 
is  an  act  of  truth  as  we  understand  it  here.  But  this  belongs 
to  every  virtue,  since  every  virtuous  habit  is  made  known 
by  its  own  act.     Therefore  truth  is  not  a  special  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  truth  of  life  is  the  truth  whereby  one 
lives  aright,  and  of  which  it  is  written  (Isa.  xxxviii.  3):  / 
beseech  Thee  .  .  remember  how  I  have  walked  before  Thee  in 
truth,  and  with  a  perfect  heart.  Now  one  lives  aright  by  any 
virtue,  as  follows  from  the  definition  of  virtue  given  above 
(I. -II.,  Q.  LV.,  A.  4).  Therefore  truth  is  not  a  special 
virtue. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Truth  seems  to  be  the  same  as  simplicity, 
since  hypocrisy  is  opposed  to  both.  But  simplicity  is  not  a 
special  virtue,  since  it  rectifies  the  intention,  and  that  is 
required  in  every  virtue.  Therefore  neither  is  truth  a 
special  virtue. 


79  TRUTH  Q.  109.  Art.  2 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  numbered  together  with  other  virtues 
(Ethic,  ii.  7). 

/  answer  that,  The  nature  of  human  virtue  consists  in 
making  a  man's  deed  good.  Consequently  whenever  we  find 
a  special  aspect  of  goodness  in  human  acts,  it  is  necessary 
that  man  be  disposed  thereto  by  a  special  virtue.  And  since 
according  to  Augustine  (De  Nat.  Boni  hi.)  good  consists  in 
order,  it  follows  that  a  special  aspect  of  good  will  be  found 
where  there  is  a  special  order.  Now  there  is  a  special  order 
whereby  our  externals,  whether  words  or  deeds,  are  duly 
ordered  in  relation  to  some  thing,  as  sign  to  thing  signified: 
and  thereto  man  is  perfected  by  the  virtue  of  truth.  Where- 
fore it  is  evident  that  truth  is  a  special  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  true  and  the  good  are  convertible  as  to 
subject,  since  every  true  thing  is  good,  and  every  good  thing 
is  true.  But  considered  logically,  they  exceed  one  another, 
even  as  the  intellect  and  will  exceed  one  another.  For  the 
intellect  understands  the  will  and  many  things  besides,  and 
the  will  desires  things  pertaining  to  the  intellect,  and  many 
others.  Wherefore  the  true  considered  in  its  proper  aspect 
as  a  perfection  of  the  intellect  is  a  particular  good,  since  it  is 
something  appetible :  and  in  like  manner  the  good  considered 
in  its  proper  aspect  as  the  end  of  the  appetite  is  something 
true,  since  it  is  something  intelligible.  Therefore  since  virtue 
includes  the  aspect  of  goodness,  it  is  possible  for  truth  to  be 
a  special  virtue,  just  as  the  true  is  a  special  good;  yet  it  is  not 
possible  for  goodness  to  be  a  special  virtue,  since  rather, 
considered  logically,  it  is  the  genus  of  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  habits  of  virtue  and  vice  take  their 
species  from  what  is  directly  intended,  and  not  from  that 
which  is  accidental  and  beside  the  intention.  Now  that  a 
man  states  that  which  concerns  himself,  belongs  to  the  virtue 
of  truth,  as  something  directly  intended:  although  it  may 
belong  to  other  virtues  consequently  and  beside  his  prin- 
cipal intention.  For  the  brave  man  intends  to  act  bravely : 
and  that  he  shows  his  fortitude  by  acting  bravely  is  a  con- 
sequence beside  his  principal  intention. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  truth  of  life  is  the  truth  whereby  a  thing 


Q.109.ART.3    THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  80 

is  true,  not  whereby  a  person  says  what  is  true.  Life  like 
anything  else  is  said  to  be  true,  from  the  fact  that  it  attains 
its  rule  and  measure,  namely,  the  divine  law;  since  rectitude 
of  life  depends  on  conformity  to  that  law.  This  truth  or 
rectitude  is  common  to  every  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Simplicity  is  so  called  from  its  opposition 
to  duplicity,  whereby,  to  wit,  a  man  shows  one  thing  out- 
wardly while  having  another  in  his  heart -  so  that  simplicity 
pertains  to  this  virtue.  And  it  rectifies  the  intention,  not 
indeed  directly  (since  this  belongs  to  every  virtue),  but  by 
excluding  duplicity,  whereby  a  man  pretends  one  thing  and 
intends  another. 

Third  Article, 
whether  truth  is  a  part  of  justice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  truth  is  not  a  part  of  justice. 
For  it  seems  proper  to  justice  to  give  another  man  his  due. 
But,  by  telling  the  truth,  one  does  not  seem  to  give  another 
man  his  due,  as  is  the  case  in  all  the  foregoing  parts  of  justice. 
Therefore  truth  is  not  a  part  of  justice. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Truth  pertains  to  the  intellect:  whereas 
justice  is  in  the  will,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LVIII.,  A.  4). 
Therefore  truth  is  not  a  part  of  justice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  According  to  Jerome  truth  is  threefold, 
namely,  truth  of  life,  truth  of  justice,  and  truth  of  doctrine. 
But  none  of  these  is  a  part  of  justice.  For  truth  of  life  com- 
prises all  virtues,  as  stated  above  (A.  2,  ad  3) :  truth  of  justice 
is  the  same  as  justice,  so  that  it  is  not  one  of  its  parts;  and 
truth  of  doctrine  belongs  rather  to  the  intellectual  virtues. 
Therefore  truth  is  nowise  a  part  of  justice. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  {De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  reckons  truth 
among  the  parts  of  justice. 

J  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  LXXX.),  a  virtue  is 
annexed  to  justice,  as  secondary  to  a  principal  virtue, 
through  having  something  in  common  with  justice,  while 
falling  short  from  the  perfect  virtue  thereof.  Now  the  virtue 
of  truth  has  two  things  in  common  with  justice.     In  the 


8i  TRUTH  Q.  109.  Art.  3 

first  place  it  is  directed  to  another,  since  the  manifestation, 
which  we  have  stated  to  be  an  act  of  truth,  is  directed  to 
another,  inasmuch  as  one  person  manifests  to  another  the 
things  that  concern  himself.  In  the  second  place,  justice 
sets  up  a  certain  equality  between  things,  and  this  the  virtue 
of  truth  does  also,  for  it  equals  signs  to  the  things  which 
concern  man  himself.  Nevertheless  it  falls  short  of  the 
proper  aspect  of  justice,  as  to  the  notion  of  debt:  for  this 
virtue  does  not  regard  legal  debt,  which  justice  considers, 
but  rather  the  moral  debt,  in  so  far  as,  out  of  equity,  one 
man  owes  another  a  manifestation  of  the  truth.  Therefore 
truth  is  a  part  of  justice,  being  annexed  thereto  as  a  secon- 
dary virtue  to  its  principal. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Since  man  is  a  social  animal,  one  man 
naturally  owes  another  whatever  is  necessary  for  the  pre- 
servation of  human  society.  Now  it  would  be  impossible 
for  men  to  live  together,  unless  they  believed  one  another, 
as  declaring  the  truth  one  to  another.  Hence  the  virtue 
of  truth  does,  in  a  manner,  regard  something  as  being  due. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Truth,  as  known,  belongs  to  the  intellect. 
But  man,  by  his  own  will,  whereby  he  uses  both  habits  and 
members,  utters  external  signs  in  order  to  manifest  the  truth, 
and  in  this  way  the  manifestation  of  the  truth  is  an  act  of 
the  will. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  truth  of  which  we  are  speaking  now 
differs  from  the  truth  of  life,  as  stated  in  the  preceding 
Article  {ad  3). 

We  speak  of  the  truth  of  justice  in  two  ways.  In  one  way 
we  refer  to  the  fact  that  justice  itself  is  a  certain  rectitude 
regulated  according  to  the  rule  of  the  divine  law;  and  in 
this  way  the  truth  of  justice  differs  from  the  truth  of  life, 
because  by  the  truth  of  life  a  man  lives  aright  in  himself, 
whereas  by  the  truth  of  justice  a  man  observes  the  rectitude 
of  the  law  in  those  judgements  which  refer  to  another  man : 
and  in  this  sense  the  truth  of  justice  has  nothing  to  do 
with  the  truth  of  which  we  speak  now,  as  neither  has  the 
truth  of  life.  In  another  way  the  truth  of  justice  may  be 
understood  as  referring  to  the  fact  that,  out  of  justice,  a 

n.  ii.  4  6 


Q.  109.  Art,  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  82 


"j 


man  manifests  the  truth,  as  for  instance  when  a  man  con- 
fesses the  truth,  or  gives  true  evidence  in  a  court  of  justice. 
This  truth  is  a  particular  act  of  justice,  and  does  not  pertain 
directly  to  this  truth  of  which  we  are  now  speaking,  because, 
to  wit,  in  this  manifestation  of  the  truth  a  man's  chief 
intention  is  to  give  another  man  his  due.  Hence  the  Philo- 
sopher says  [Ethic,  iv.  7)  in  describing  this  virtue :  We  are  not 
speaking  of  one  who  is  truthful  in  his  agreements,  nor  does  this 
apply  to  matters  in  which  justice  or  injustice  is  questioned. 

The  truth  of  doctrine  consists  in  a  certain  manifestation 
of  truths  relating  to  science.  Wherefore  neither  does  this 
truth  directly  pertain  to  this  virtue,  but  only  that  truth 
whereby  a  man,  both  in  life  and  in  speech,  shows  himself 
to  be  such  as  he  is,  and  the  things  that  concern  him,  not 
other,  and  neither  greater  nor  less,  than  they  are.  Never- 
theless since  truths  of  science,  as  known  by  us,  are  something 
concerning  us,  and  pertain  to  us,  in  this  sense  the  truth 
of  doctrine  may  pertain  to  this  virtue,  as  well  as  any  other 
kind  of  truth  whereby  a  man  manifests,  by  word  or  deed, 
what  he  knows. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  virtue  of  truth  inclines  rather  to  that 

which  is  less  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  virtue  of  truth  does  not 
incline  to  that  which  is  less.  For  as  one  incurs  falsehood 
by  saying  more,  so  does  one  by  saying  less :  thus  it  is  no  more 
false  that  four  are  five,  than  that  four  are  three.  But  every 
falsehood  is  in  itself  evil,  and  to  be  avoided,  as  the  Philosopher 
declares  [Ethic,  iv.  7).  Therefore  the  virtue  of  truth  does  not 
incline  to  that  which  is  less  rather  than  to  that  which  is 
greater. 

Obj.  2.  Further.  That  a  virtue  inclines  to  the  one  extreme 
rather  than  to  the  other,  is  owing  to  the  fact  that  the  virtue's 
mean  is  nearer  to  the  one  extreme  than  to  the  other :  thus 
fortitude  is  nearer  to  daring  than  to  timidity.  But  the 
mean  of  truth  is  not  nearer  to  one  extreme  than  to  the 


83  TRUTH  Q.  109.  Art.  4 

other;  because  truth,  since  it  is  a  kind  of  equality,  holds  to 
the  exact  mean.  Therefore  truth  does  not  more  incline  to 
that  which  is  less. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  To  forsake  the  truth  for  that  which  is 
less  seems  to  amount  to  a  denial  of  the  truth,  since  this  is  to 
subtract  therefrom ;  and  to  forsake  the  truth  for  that  which 
is  greater  seems  to  amount  to  an  addition  thereto.  Now  to 
deny  the  truth  is  more  repugnant  to  truth  than  to  add  some- 
thing to  it,  because  truth  is  incompatible  with  the  denial  of 
truth,  whereas  it  is  compatible  with  addition.  Therefore  it 
seems  that  truth  should  incline  to  that  which  is  greater  rather 
than  to  that  which  is  less. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  7)  that 
by  this  virtue  a  man  inclines  rather  from  the  truth  towards 
that  which  is  less. 

I  answer  that,  There  are  two  ways  of  inclining  from  the 
truth  to  that  which  is  less.  First,  by  affirming,  as  when  a 
man  does  not  show  the  whole  good  that  is  in  him,  for  instance 
science,  holiness  and  so  forth.  This  is  done  without  prejudice 
to  truth,  since  the  lesser  is  contained  in  the  greater :  and  in 
this  way  this  virtue  inclines  to  what  is  less.  For,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  (ibid.) ,  this  seems  to  be  more  prudent  because 
exaggerations  give  annoyance.  For  those  who  represent 
themselves  as  being  greater  than  they  are,  are  a  source  of  annoy- 
ance to  others,  since  they  seem  to  wish  to  surpass  others: 
whereas  those  who  make  less  account  of  themselves  are  a  source 
of  pleasure,  since  they  seem  to  defer  to  others  by  their  modera- 
tion. Hence  the  Apostle  says  (2  Cor.  xii.  6)  :  Though  I 
should  have  a  mind  to  glory,  I  shall  not  be  foolish  :  for  I  will 
say  the  truth.  But  I  forbear,  lest  any  man  should  think  of 
me  above  that  which  he  seeth  in  me,  or  anything  he  heareth 
from  me. 

Secondly,  one  may  incline  to  what  is  less  by  denying,  so 
as  to  say  that  what  is  in  us  is  not.  In  this  way  it  does  not 
belong  to  this  virtue  to  incline  to  what  is  less,  because  this 
would  imply  falsehood.  And  yet  this  would  be  less  repug- 
nant to  the  truth,  not  indeed  as  regards  the  proper  aspect  of 
truth,  but  as  regards  the  aspect  of  prudence,  which  should 


Q.  iog.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  84 

be  safeguarded  in  all  the  virtues.  For  since  it  is  fraught 
with  greater  danger  and  is  more  annoying  to  others,  it  is 
more  repugnant  to  prudence  to  think  or  boast  that  one  has 
what  one  has  not,  than  to  think  or  say  that  one  has  not  what 
one  has. 

This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Objections. 


QUESTION  CX. 

OF  THE  VICES  OPPOSED  TO  TRUTH,  AND  FIRST  OF 

LYING. 

(In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  vices  opposed  to  truth,  and  (i) 
lying:  (2)  dissimulation  or  hypocrisy:  (3)  boasting  and  the 
opposite  vice.  Concerning  lying  there  are  four  points  of 
inquiry:  (1)  Whether  lying,  as  containing  falsehood,  is 
always  opposed  to  truth  ?  (2)  Of  the  species  of  lying  : 
(3)  Whether  lying  is  always  a  sin  ?  (4)  Whether  it  is  always 
a  mortal  sin  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  lying  is  always  opposed  to  truth  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  lying  is  not  always  opposed 
to  truth.  For  opposites  are  incompatible  with  one  another. 
But  lying  is  compatible  with  truth,  since  he  that  speaks  the 
truth,  thinking  it  to  be  false,  lies,  according  to  Augustine 
(Contra  Mendac.  iii.).  Therefore  lying  is  not  opposed  to 
truth. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  virtue  of  truth  applies  not  only  to 
words  but  also  to  deeds,  since  according  to  the  Philosopher 
(Ethic,  iv.  7)  by  this  virtue  one  tells  the  truth  both  in  one's 
speech  and  in  one's  life.  But  lying  applies  only  to  words, 
for  Augustine  says  (Contra  Mend,  xii.)  that  a  lie  is  a  false 
signification  by  words.  Accordingly,  it  seems  that  lying  is  not 
directly  opposed  to  the  virtue  of  truth. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  (Contra  Mend.,  loc.  cit.) 
that  the  liar's  sin  is  the  desire  to  deceive.     But  this  is  not 

85 


Q.  1 10.  Art.  i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  86 

opposed  to  truth,  but  rather  to  benevolence  or  justice. 
Therefore  lying  is  not  opposed  to  truth. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Contra  Mend,  x.):  Let 
no  one  doubt  that  it  is  a  lie  to  tell  a  falsehood  in  order  to  deceive. 
Wherefore  a  false  staten  ent  uttered  with  intent  to  deceive  is 
a  manifest  lie.  But  this  is  opposed  to  truth.  Therefore 
lying  is  opposed  to  truth. 

/  answer  that,  A  moral  act  takes  its  species  from  two  things, 
its  object,  and  its  end:  for  the  end  is  the  object  of  the  will, 
which  is  the  first  mover  in  moral  acts.  And  the  power 
moved  by  the  will  has  its  own  object,  which  is  the  proximate 
object  of  the  voluntary  act,  and  stands  in  relation  to  the 
will's  act  towards  the  end,  as  material  to  formal,  as  stated 
above  ( I.-IL,  Q.  XVIII.,  AA.  6,  7). 

Now  it  has  been  said  above  (Q.  CIX.,  A.i,  ad  3)  that 
the  virtue  of  truth — and  consequently  the  opposite  vices — 
regards  a  manifestation  made  by  certain  signs:  and  this 
manifestation  or  statement  is  an  act  of  reason  comparing 
sign  with  the  thing  signified ;  because  every  representation 
consists  in  comparison,  which  is  the  proper  act  of  the  reason. 
Wherefore  though  dumb  animals  manifest  something,  yet 
they  do  not  intend  to  manifest  anything:  but  they  do 
something  by  natural  instinct,  and  a  manifestation  is  the 
result.  But  when  this  manifestation  or  statement  is  a  moral 
act,  it  must  needs  be  voluntary,  and  dependent  on  the 
intention  of  the  will.  Now  the  proper  object  of  a  manifesta- 
tion or  statement  is  the  true  or  the  false.  And  the  intention 
of  a  bad  will  may  bear  on  two  things :  one  of  which  is  that 
a  falsehood  may  be  told;  while  the  other  is  the  proper  effect 
of  a  false  statement,  namely,  that  someone  may  be  deceived. 

Accordingly  if  these  three  things  concur,  namely,  falsehood 
of  what  is  said,  the  will  to  tell  a  falsehood,  and  finally  the 
intention  to  deceive,  then  there  is  falsehood — materially, 
since  what  is  said  is  false,  formally,  on  account  of  the  will 
to  tell  an  untruth,  and  effectively,  on  account  of  the  will 
to  impart  a  falsehood. 

However,  the  essential  notion  of  a  lie  is  taken  from  formal 
falsehood,  from  the  fact,  namely,  that  a  person  intends  to 


87  LYING  Q.  no.  Art.  i 

say  what  is  false;  wherefore  also  the  word  mendacium  (lie) 
is  derived  from  its  being  in  opposition  to  the  mind.  Conse- 
quently if  one  says  what  is  false,  thinking  it  to  be  true,  it 
is  false  materially,  but  not  formally,  because  the  falseness  is 
beside  the  intention  of  the  speaker :  so  that  it  is  not  a  perfect 
lie,  since  what  is  beside  the  speaker's  intention  is  accidental, 
for  which  reason  it  cannot  be  a  specific  difference.  If,  on 
the  other  hand,  one  utters  a  falsehood  formally,  through 
having  the  will  to  deceive,  even  if  what  one  says  be  true, 
yet  inasmuch  as  this  is  a  voluntary  and  moral  act,  it 
contains  falseness  essentially  and  truth  accidentally,  and 
attains  the  specific  nature  of  a  lie. 

That  a  person  intends  to  cause  another  to  have  a  false 
opinion,  by  deceiving  him,  does  not  belong  to  the  species 
of  lying,  but  to  a  perfection  thereof,  even  as  in  the  physical 
order,  a  thing  acquires  its  species  if  it  has  its  form,  even 
though  the  form's  effect  be  lacking;  for  instance  a  heavy 
body  which  is  held  up  aloft  by  force,  lest  it  come  down  in 
accordance  with  the  exigency  of  its  form.  Therefore  it  is 
evident  that  lying  is  directly  and  formally  opposed  to  the 
virtue  of  truth. 

Re  fly  Obj.  i.  We  judge  of  a  thing  according  to  what  is 
in  it  formally  and  essentially,  rather  than  according  to  what 
is  in  it  materially  and  accidentally.  Hence  it  is  more  in 
opposition  to  truth,  considered  as  a  moral  virtue,  to  tell  the 
truth  with  the  intention  of  telling  a  falsehood  than  to  tell  a 
falsehood  with  the  intention  of  telling  the  truth. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  Augustine  says  {De  Doctr.  Christ,  ii.), 
words  hold  the  chief  place  among  other  signs.  And  so 
when  it  is  said  that  a.  lie  is  a  false  signification  by  words,  the 
term  words  denotes  every  kind  of  sign.  Wherefore  if  a 
person  intended  to  signify  something  false  by  means  of  signs, 
he  would  not  be  excused  from  lying. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  desire  to  deceive  belongs  to  the  per- 
fection of  lying,  but  not  to  its  species,  as  neither  does  any 
effect  belong  to  the  species  of  its  cause. 


Q.  no.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  88 


Second  Article. 

whether  lies  are  sufficiently  divided  into  officious, 
jocose  and  mischievous  lies  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  lies  are  not  sufficiently  divided 
into  officious,  jocose  and  mischievous  lies.  For  a  division 
should  be  made  according  to  that  which  pertains  to  a  thing 
by  reason  of  its  nature,  as  the  Philosopher  states  (MeUph. 
vii.  text.  43:  De  Part.  Animal,  i.  3).  But  seemingly  the 
intention  of  the  effect  resulting  from  a  moral  act  is  some- 
thing beside  and  accidental  to  the  species  of  that  act,  so 
that  an  indefinite  number  of  effects  can  result  from  one 
act.  Now  this  division  is  made  according  to  the  intention 
of  the  effect :  for  a  jocose  lie  is  told  in  order  to  make  fun,  an 
officious  lie  for  some  useful  purpose,  and  a  mischievous  he 
in  order  to  injure  someone.  Therefore  lies  are  unfittingly 
divided  in  this  way. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Augustine  (Contra  Mendac.  xiv.)  gives 
eight  kinds  of  lies.  The  first  is  in  religious  doctrine;  the 
second  is  a  lie  that  profits  no  one  and  injures  someone ;  the 
third  profits  one  party  so  as  to  injure  another  ;  the  fourth  is 
told  out  of  mere  lust  of  lying  and  deceiving;  the  fifth  is  told 
out  of  the  desire  to  please  ;  the  sixth  injures  no  one,  and  profits 
someone  in  saving  his  money  ;  the  seventh  injures  no  one  and 
profits  someone  in  saving  him  from  death  ;  the  eighth  injures  no 
one,  and  profits  someone  in  saving  him  from  defilement  of  the 
body.  Therefore  it  seems  that  the  first  division  of  lies  is 
insufficient. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  7)  divides 
lying  into  boasting,  which  exceeds  the  truth  in  speech,  and 
irony,  which  falls  short  of  the  truth  by  saying  something 
less:  and  these  two  are  not  contained  under  any  one  of 
the  kinds  mentioned  above.  Therefore  it  seems  that  the 
aforesaid  division  of  lies  is  inadequate. 

On  the  contrary,  A  gloss  on  Ps.  v.  7,  Thou  wilt  destroy  all 
that  speak  a  lie,  says  that  there  are  three  kinds  of  lies  ;  for  some 


89  LYING  Q.  tio.akt.2 

are  told  for  the  wellbeing  and  convenience  of  someone',  and 
there  is  another  kind  of  lie  that  is  told  in  fun  ;  but  the  third 
kind  of  lie  is  told  out  of  malice.  The  first  of  these  is  called 
an  officious  lie,  the  second  a  jocose  lie,  the  third  a  mis- 
chievous lie.  Therefore  lies  are  divided  into  these  three 
kinds. 

/  answer  that,  Lies  may  be  divided  in  three  ways.  First, 
with  respect  to  their  nature  as  lies:  and  this  is  the  proper 
and  essential  division  of  lying.  In  this  way,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  {Ethic,  iv.  7),  lies  are  of  two  kinds,  namely,  the 
lie  which  goes  beyond  the  truth,  and  this  belongs  to  boasting, 
and  the  lie  which  stops  short  of  the  truth,  and  this  belongs 
to  irony.  This  division  is  an  essential  division  of  lying 
itself,  because  lying  as  such  is  opposed  to  truth,  as  stated 
in  the  preceding  Article:  and  truth  is  a  kind  of  equalitj',  to 
which  more  and  less  are  in  essential  opposition. 

Secondly,  lies  may  be  divided  with  respect  to  their  nature 
as  sins,  and  with  regard  to  those  things  that  aggravate  or 
diminish  the  sin  of  lying,  on  the  part  of  the  end  intended. 
Now  the  sin  of  lying  is  aggravated,  if  by  lying  a  person  intends 
to  injure  another,  and  this  is  called  a  mischievous  lie,  while 
the  sin  of  lying  is  diminished  if  it  be  directed  to  some  good — 
either  of  pleasure  and  then  it  is  a  jocose  lie,  or  of  usefulness, 
and  then  we  have  the  officious  lie,  whereby  it  is  intended  to 
help  another  person,  or  to  save  him  from  being  injured.  In 
this  way  lies  are  divided  into  the  three  kinds  aforesaid. 

Thirdly,  lies  are  divided  in  a  more  general  way,  with 
respect  to  their  relation  to  some  end,  whether  or  not  this 
increase  or  diminish  their  gravity :  and  in  this  way  the  divi- 
sion comprises  eight  kinds,  as  stated  in  the  Second  Objection. 
Here  the  first  three  kinds  are  contained  under  mischievous 
lies,  which  are  either  against  God,  and  then  we  have  the  lie 
in  religious  doctrine,  or  against  man,  and  this  either  with 
the  sole  intention  of  injuring  him,  and  then  it  is  the  second 
kind  of  lie,  which  profits  no  one,  and  injures  someone;  or  with 
the  intention  of  injuring  one  and  at  the  same  time  profiting 
another,  and  this  is  the  third  kind  of  lie,  which  profits  one, 
and  injures  another.     Of  these  the  first  is  the  most  grievous, 


Q.  no.  Art,  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  go 

because  sins  against  God  are  always  more  grievous,  as  stated 
above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXXIIL,  A.  9):  and  the  second  is  more 
grievous  than  the  third,  since  the  latter's  gravity  is  dimin- 
ished by  the  intention  of  profiting  another. 

After  these  three,  which  aggravate  the  sin  of  lying,  we 
have  a  fourth,  which  has  its  own  measure  of  gravity  with- 
out addition  or  diminution,  and  this  is  the  lie  which  is  told 
out  of  mere  lust  of  lying  and  deceiving.  This  proceeds  from 
the  habit,  wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  7)  that 
the  liar,  since  he  lies  from  habit,  delights  in  lying. 

The  four  kinds  that  follow  lessen  the  gravity  of  the  sin 
of  lying.  For  the  fifth  kind  is  the  jocose  lie,  which  is  told 
with  a  desire  to  please :  and  the  remaining  three  are  comprised 
under  the  officious  lie,  wherein  something  useful  to  another 
person  is  intended.  This  usefulness  regards  either  external 
things,  and  then  we  have  the  sixth  kind  of  lie,  which  profits 
someone  in  saving  his  money;  or  his  body,  and  this  is  the 
seventh  kind,  which  saves  a  man  from  death;  or  the  morality 
of  his  virtue,  and  this  is  the  eighth  kind,  which  saves  him 
from  unlawful  defilement  of  his  body. 

Now  it  is  evident  that  the  greater  the  good  intended,  the 
more  is  the  sin  of  lying  diminished  in  gravity.  Wherefore 
a  careful  consideration  of  the  matter  will  show  that  these 
various  kinds  of  lies  are  enumerated  in  their  order  of  gravity : 
since  the  useful  good  is  better  than  the  pleasurable  good, 
and  life  of  the  body  than  money,  and  virtue  than  the  life 
of  the  body. 

This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Objections. 

Third  Article, 
whether  every  lie  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  not  every  lie  is  a  sin.  For  it  is 
evident  that  the  evangelists  did  not  sin  in  the  writing  of  the 
Gospel.  Yet  they  seem  to  have  told  something  false :  since 
their  accounts  of  the  words  of  Christ  and  of  others  often 
differ  from  one  another:  wherefore  seemingly  one  of  them 


91  LYING  Q.  no.  Art.  3 

must  have  given  an  untrue  account.     Therefore  not  every 
lie  is  a  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  No  one  is  rewarded  by  God  for  sin.  But 
the  mid  wives  of  Egypt  were  rewarded  by  God  for  a  lie,  for 
it  is  stated  that  God  built  them  houses  (Exod.  i.  21).  There- 
fore a  lie  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  deeds  of  holy  men  are  related  in 
Sacred  Writ  that  they  may  be  a  model  of  human  life.  But 
we  read  of  certain  very  holy  men  that  they  lied.  Thus 
(Gen.  xii.  and  xx.)  we  are  told  that  Abraham  said  of  his  wife 
that  she  was  his  sister.  Jacob  also  lied  when  he  said  that  he 
was  Esau,  and  yet  he  received  a  blessing  (Gen.  xxvii.  27-29). 
Again,  Judith  is  commended  (Judith  xv.  10,  11)  although 
she  lied  to  Holofernes.     Therefore  not  every  lie  is  a  sin. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  One  ought  to  choose  the  lesser  evil  in 
order  to  avoid  the  greater :  even  so  a  physician  cuts  off  a 
limb,  lest  the  whole  body  perish.  Yet  less  harm  is  done  by 
raising  a  false  opinion  in  a  person's  mind,  than  by  someone 
slaying  or  being  slain.  Therefore  a  man  may  lawfully  lie, 
to  save  another  from  committing  murder,  or  another  from 
being  killed. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  It  is  a  lie  not  to  fulfil  what  one  has 
promised.  Yet  one  is  not  bound  to  keep  all  one's  promises: 
for  Isidore  says  (Synonym,  ii.) :  Break  your  faith  when  you 
have  promised  ill.     Therefore  not  every  lie  is  a  sin. 

Obj.  6.  Further,  Apparently  a  lie  is  a  sin  because  thereby 
we  deceive  our  neighbour :  wherefore  Augustine  says  (Contra 
Mend,  xxi.) :  Whoever  thinks  that  there  is  any  kind  of  lie  that 
is  not  a  sin  deceives  himself  shamefully,  since  he  deems  him- 
self an  honest  man  when  he  deceives  others.  Yet  not  every 
lie  is  a  cause  of  deception,  since  no  one  is  deceived  by  a 
jocose  lie;  seeing  that  lies  of  this  kind  are  told,  not  with  the 
intention  of  being  believed,  but  merely  for  the  sake  of  giving 
pleasure.  Hence  again  we  find  hyperbolical  expressions  in 
Holy  Writ.     Therefore  not  every  lie  is  a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ecclus.  vii.  14):  Be  not 
willing  to  make  any  manner  of  lie. 

I  answer  that,  An  action  that  is  naturally  evil  in  respect 


Quo.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  92 

of  its  genus  can  by  no  means  be  good  and  lawful,  since  in 
order  for  an  action  to  be  good  it  must  be  right  in  every 
respect:  because  good  results  from  a  complete  cause,  while 
evil  results  from  any  single  defect,  as  Dionysius  asserts 
(Div.  Nont.  iv.).  Now  a  he  is  evil  in  respect  of  its  genus, 
since  it  is  an  action  bearing  on  undue  matter.  For  as  words 
are  naturally  signs  of  intellectual  acts,  it  is  unnatural  and 
undue  for  anyone  to  signify  by  words  something  that  is 
not  in  his  mind.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  7) 
that  lying  is  in  itself  evil  and  to  be  shunned,  while  truthfulness 
is  good  and  worthy  of  praise.  Therefore  every  he  is  a  sin, 
as  also  Augustine  declares  (Contra  Mend.  i.). 

Reply  Obj,  1.  It  is  unlawful  to  hold  that  any  false  assertion 
is  contained  either  in  the  Gospel  or  in  any  canonical  Scrip- 
ture, or  that  the  writers  thereof  have  told  untruths,  because 
faith  would  be  deprived  of  its  certitude  which  is  based  on 
the  authority  of  Holy  Writ.  That  the  words  of  certain 
people  are  variously  reported  in  the  Gospel  and  other  sacred 
writings  does  not  constitute  a  lie.  Hence  Augustine  says 
(De  Consens.  Evang.  ii.) :  He  that  has  the  wit  to  understand 
that  in  order  to  know  the  truth  it  is  necessary  to  get  at  the  sense, 
will  conclude  that  he  must  not  be  the  least  troubled,  no  matter 
by  what  words  that  sense  is  expressed.  Hence  it  is  evident, 
as  he  adds  (ibid.),  that  we  must  not  judge  that  someone  is 
lying,  if  several  persons  fail  to  describe  in  the  same  way  and 
in  the  same  words  a  thing  which  they  remember  to  have  seen 
or  heard. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  midwives  were  rewarded,  not  for  their 
lie,  but  for  their  fear  of  God,  and  for  their  good-will,  which 
latter  led  them  to  tell  a  lie.  Hence  it  is  expressly  stated 
(Exod.  ii.  21) :  And  because  the  midwives  feared  God,  He  built 
them  houses.     But  the  subsequent  lie  was  not  meritorious. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  Holy  Writ,  as  Augustine  observes 
(Contra  Mend,  v.),  the  deeds  of  certain  persons  are  related 
as  examples  of  perfect  virtue :  and  we  must  not  believe  that 
such  persons  were  liars.  If,  however,  any  of  their  statements 
appear  to  be  untruthful,  we  must  understand  such  statements 
to  have  been  figurative  and  prophetic.    Hence  Augustine  says 


93  LYING  Q.  no.  Art.  3 

(Contra  Mend.,  loc.  cit.):  We  must  believe  that  whatever  is 
related  of  those  who,  in  prophetical  times,  are  mentioned  as  being 
worthy  of  credit,  was  done  and  said  by  them  prophetically. 
As  to  Abraham  when  he  said  that  Sara  was  his  sister,  he 
wished  to  hide  the  truth,  not  to  tell  a  lie,  for  she  is  called  his 
sister  since  she  was  the  daughter  of  his  father,  as  Augustine 
says  (QQ.  Super.  Gen.  xxvi. :  Contra  Mend.  x. :  Contra  Faust. 
xxii.).  Wherefore  Abraham  himself  said  (Gen.  xx.  12): 
She  is  truly  my  sister,  the  daughter  of  my  father,  and  not  the 
daughter  of  my  mother,  being  related  to  him  on  his  father's 
side.  Jacob's  assertion  that  he  was  Esau,  Isaac's  first-born, 
was  spoken  in  a  mystical  sense,  because,  to  wit,  the  latter's 
birthright  was  due  to  him  by  right :  and  he  made  use  of  this 
mode  of  speech  being  moved  by  the  spirit  of  prophecy,  in 
order  to  signify  a  mystery,  namely,  that  the  younger  people, 
i.e.  the  Gentiles,  should  supplant  the  first-born,  i.e.  the  Jews. 

Some,  however,  are  commended  in  the  Scriptures,  not  on 
account  of  perfect  virtue,  but  for  a  certain  virtuous  disposi- 
tion, seeing  that  it  was  owing  to  some  praiseworthy  senti- 
ment that  they  were  moved  to  do  certain  undue  things. 
It  is  thus  that  Judith  is  praised,  not  for  lying  to  Holof  ernes, 
but  for  her  desire  to  save  the  people,  to  which  end  she 
exposed  herself  to  danger.  And  yet  one  might  also  say  that 
her  words  contain  truth  in  some  mystical  sense. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  A  lie  is  sinful  not  only  because  it  injures 
one's  neighbour,  but  also  on  account  of  its  inordinateness, 
as  stated  above  in  this  Article.  Now  it  is  not  allowed  to 
make  use  of  anything  inordinate  in  order  to  ward  off  injury 
or  defects  from  another:  as  neither  is  it  lawful  to  steal  in 
order  to  give  an  alms,  except  perhaps  in  a  case  of  necessity 
when  all  things  are  common.  Therefore  it  is  not  lawful 
to  tell  a  lie  in  order  to  deliver  another  from  any  danger 
whatever.  Nevertheless  it  is  lawful  to  hide  the  truth 
prudently,  by  keeping  it  back,  as  Augustine  says  (Contra 
Mend.  x.). 

Reply  Obj.  5.  A  man  does  not  lie,  so  long  as  he  has  a  mind 
to  do  what  he  promises,  because  he  does  not  speak  contrary 
to  what  he  has  in  mind :  but  if  he  does  not  keep  his  promise, 


Q.  no.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  94 

he  seems  to  act  without  faith  in  changing  his  mind.  He 
may,  however,  be  excused  for  two  reasons.  First,  if  he  has 
promised  something  evidently  unlawful,  because  he  sinned 
in  promise,  and  did  well  to  change  his  mind.  Secondly, 
if  circumstances  have  changed  with  regard  to  persons  and 
the  business  in  hand.  For,  as  Seneca  states  (De  Bene/,  iv.), 
for  a  man  to  be  bound  to  keep  a  promise  it  is  necessary  for 
everything  to  remain  unchanged :  otherwise  neither  did  he 
lie  in  promising — since  he  promised  what  he  had  in  his 
mind,  due  circumstances  being  taken  for  granted — nor  was 
he  faithless  in  not  keeping  his  promise,  because  circum- 
stances are  no  longer  the  same.  Hence  the  Apostle,  though 
he  did  not  go  to  Corinth,  whither  he  had  promised  to  go 
(2  Cor.  i.),  did  not  lie,  because  obstacles  had  arisen  which 
prevented  him. 

Reply  Obj.  6.  An  action  may  be  considered  in  two  ways. 
First,  in  itself,  secondly,  with  regard  to  the  agent.  Ac- 
cordingly a  jocose  lie,  from  the  very  genus  of  the  action,  is 
of  a  nature  to  deceive;  although  in  the  intention  of  the 
speaker  it  is  not  told  to  deceive,  nor  does  it  deceive  by  the 
way  it  is  told.  Nor  is  there  any  similarity  in  the  hyperbolical 
or  any  kind  of  figurative  expressions,  with  which  we  meet 
in  Holy  Writ:  because,  as  Augustine  says  {Contra  Mend,  v.), 
it  is  not  a  lie  to  do  or  say  a  thing  figuratively  :  because  every 
statement  must  be  referred  to  the  thing  stated :  and  when  a 
thing  is  done  or  said  figuratively ,  it  states  what  those  to  whom 
it  is  tendered  understand  it  to  signify. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether   every  lie  is  a  mortal  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  every  lie  is  a  mortal  sin.  For  it 
is  written  (Ps.  vi.  7) :  Thou  wilt  destroy  all  that  speak  a  lie, 
and  (Wis.  i.  11) :  The  mouth  that  belieth  killeth  the  soul.  Now 
mortal  sin  alone  causes  destruction  and  death  of  the  soul. 
Therefore  every  lie  is  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Whatever  is  against  a  precept   of   the 


95  LYING  Quo.  Art.  4 

decalogue  is  a  mortal  sin.  Now  lying  is  against  this  precept 
of  the  decalogue :  Thou  shalt  not  bear  false  witness.  There- 
fore every  lie  is  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  (De  Doctr.  Christ,  i.  36) : 
Every  liar  breaks  his  faith  in  lying,  since  forsooth  he  wishes 
the  person  to  whom  he  lies  to  have  faith  in  him,  and  yet  he  does 
not  keep  faith  with  him,  when  he  lies  to  him  :  and  whoever 
breaks  his  faith  is  guilty  of  iniquity.  Now  no  one  is  said  to 
break  his  faith  or  to  be  guilty  of  iniquity,  for  a  venial  sin. 
Therefore  no  lie  is  a  venial  sin. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  The  eternal  reward  is  not  lost  save  for 
a  mortal  sin.  Now,  for  a  lie  the  eternal  reward  was  lost, 
being  exchanged  for  a  temporal  meed.  For  Gregory  says 
{Moral,  xviii.)  that  we  learn  from  the  reward  of  the  midwives 
what  the  sin  of  lying  deserves  :  since  the  reward  which  they 
deserved  for  their  kindness,  and  which  they  might  have  received 
in  eternal  life,  dwindled  into  a  temporal  meed  on  account  of  the 
lie  of  which  they  were  guilty.  Therefore  even  an  officious  lie, 
such  as  was  that  of  the  midwives,  which  seemingly  is  the 
least  of  lies,  is  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  Augustine  says  [Contra  Mend,  xvii.) 
that  it  is  a  precept  of  perfection,  not  only  not  to  lie  at  all,  but 
not  even  to  wish  to  lie.  Now  it  is  a  mortal  sin  to  act  against 
a  precept.  Therefore  every  lie  of  the  perfect  is  a  mortal 
sin :  and  consequently  so  also  is  a  He  told  by  anyone  else, 
otherwise  the  perfect  would  be  worse  off  than  others. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  on  Ps.  v.  7,  Thou  wilt 
destroy,  etc. :  There  are  two  kinds  of  lie,  that  are  not  grievously 
sinful  yet  are  not  devoid  of  sin,  when  we  lie  either  in  joking, 
or  for  the  sake  of  our  neighbour' s  good.  But  every  mortal 
sin  is  grievous.  Therefore  jocose  and  officious  lies  are  not 
mortal  sins. 

/  answer  that,  A  mortal  sin  is,  properly  speaking,  one  that 
is  contrary  to  charity  whereby  the  soul  lives  in  union  with 
God,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXIV.,  A.  12;  Q.  XXXV.,  A.  3). 
Now  a  lie  may  be  contrary  to  charity  in  three  ways :  first, 
in  itself;  secondly,  in  respect  of  the  evil  intended;  thirdly, 
accidentally. 


().  no.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  96 

A  lie  may  be  in  itself  contrary  to  charity  by  reason  of  its 
false  signification.  For  if  this  be  about  divine  things,  it  is 
contrary  to  the  charity  of  God,  whose  truth  one  hides  or 
corrupts  by  such  a  lie;  so  that  a  lie  of  this  kind  is  opposed 
not  only  to  the  virtue  of  charity,  but  also  to  the  virtues  of 
faith  and  religion:  wherefore  it  is  a  most  grievous  and  a 
mortal  sin.  If,  however,  the  false  signification  be  about 
something  the  knowledge  of  which  affects  a  man's  good, 
for  instance  if  it  pertain  to  the  perfection  of  science  or  to 
moral  conduct,  a  lie  of  this  description  inflicts  an  injury  on 
one's  neighbour,  since  it  causes  him  to  have  a  false  opinion, 
wherefore  it  is  contrary  to  charity,  as  regards  the  love  of  our 
neighbour,  and  consequently  is  a  mortal  sin  On  the  other 
hand,  if  the  false  opinion  engendered  by  the  lie  be  about 
some  matter  the  knowledge  of  which  is  of  no  consequence, 
then  the  he  in  question  does  no  harm  to  one's  neighbour: 
for  instance,  if  a  person  be  deceived  as  to  some  contingent 
particulars  that  do  not  concern  him.  Wherefore  a  lie  of 
this  kind,  considered  in  itself,  is  not  a  mortal  sin. 

As  regards  the  end  in  view,  a  he  may  be  contrary  to 
charity,  through  being  told  with  the  purpose  of  injuring 
God,  and  this  is  always  a  mortal  sin,  for  it  is  opposed  to 
religion;  or  in  order  to  injure  one's  neighbour,  in  his  person, 
his  possessions  or  his  good  name,  and  this  also  is  a  mortal 
sin,  since  it  is  a  mortal  sin  to  injure  one's  neighbour,  and 
one  sins  mortally  if  one  has  merely  the  intention  of  com- 
mitting a  mortal  sin.  But  if  the  end  intended  be  not 
contrary  to  charity,  neither  will  the  lie,  considered  under 
this  aspect,  be  a  mortal  sin,  as  in  the  case  of  a  jocose  lie, 
where  some  little  pleasure  is  intended,  or  in  an  officious 
lie,  where  the  good  also  of  one's  neighbour  is  intended. 
Accidentally  a  lie  may  be  contrary  to  charity  by  reason  of 
scandal  or  any  other  injury  resulting  therefrom:  and  thus 
again  it  will  be  a  mortal  sin,  for  instance  if  a  man  were  not 
deterred  through  scandal  from  lying  publicly. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  passages  quoted  refer  to  the  mis- 
chievous he,  as  a  gloss  explains  the  words  of  Ps.  v.  7,  Thou 
wilt  destroy  all  that  speak  a  lie. 


97  LYING  Q.  no.  Art.  4 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Since  all  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are 
directed  to  the  love  of  God  and  our  neighbour,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XLIV.,  A.  1,  ad  3 :  I. -II.,  Q.  C,  A.  5,  ad  1),  a  lie  is 
contrary  to  a  precept  of  the  decalogue,  in  so  far  as  it  is 
contrary  to  the  love  of  God  and  our  neighbour.  Hence  it 
is  expressly  forbidden  to  bear  false  witness  against  our 
neighbour. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Even  a  venial  sin  can  be  called  iniquity  in 
a  broad  sense,  in  so  far  as  it  is  beside  the  equity  of  justice; 
wherefore  it  is  written  (1  John  iii.  4) :  Every*  sin  is  iniquity. 
It  is  in  this  sense  that  Augustine  is  speaking. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  The  lie  of  the  midwives  may  be  considered 
in  two  ways.     First  as  regards  their  feeling  of  kindliness 
towards    the  Jews,  and  their  reverence  and  fear  of  God, 
for  which  their  virtuous  disposition  is  commended.     For 
this  an  eternal  reward  is  due.     Wherefore  Jerome  (in  his 
exposition   of   Isa.  lxv.  21,  And   they  shall  build  houses) 
explains  that  God  built  them  spiritual  houses.    Secondly,  it 
may   be   considered   with   regard   to   the   external  act  of 
lying.     For  thereby  they  could  merit,  not  indeed  eternal 
reward,  but  perhaps  some  temporal  meed,  the  deserving 
of    which    was    not    inconsistent    with    the    deformity  of 
their  lie,  though  this  was  inconsistent  with  their  meriting 
an  eternal  reward.     It  is  in  this  sense  that  we  must  under- 
stand the  words  of  Gregory,  and  not  that  they  merited  by 
that  lie  to  lose  the  eternal  reward  as  though  they  had  already 
merited.it  by  their  preceding  kindliness,  as  the  objection 
understands  the  words  to  mean. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  Some  say  that  for  the  perfect  every  lie  is 
a  mortal  sin.  But  this  assertion  is  unreasonable.  For  no 
circumstance  causes  a  sin  to  be  infinitely  more  grievous 
unless  it  transfers  it  to  another  species.  Now  a  circumstance 
of  person  does  not  transfer  a  sin  to  another  species,  except 
perhaps  by  reason  of  something  annexed  to  that  person, 
for  instance  if  it  be  against  his  vow :  and  this  cannot  apply 
to  an  officious  or  jocose  lie.  Wherefore  an  officious  or  a 
jocose  lie  is  not  a  mortal  sin  in  perfect  men,  except  perhaps 

*  Vulg., — And  sin  is  iniquity. 
II.  ii.  4  7 


Q.  no.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  98 

accidentally  on  account  of  scandal.  We  may  take  in 
this  sense  the  saying  of  Augustine  that  it  is  a  precept  of 
perfection  not  only  not  to  lie  at  all,  but  not  even  to  wish  to  lie: 
although  Augustine  says  this  not  positively  but  dubiously, 
for  he  begins  by  saying  Unless  perhaps  it  is  a  precept,  etc. 
Nor  does  it  matter  that  they  are  placed  in  a  position  to 
safeguard  the  truth:  because  they  are  bound  to  safeguard 
the  truth  by  virtue  of  their  office  in  judging  or  teaching,  and 
if  they  lie  in  these  matters  their  lie  will  be  a  mortal  sin :  but 
it  does  not  follow  that  they  sin  mortally  when  they  lie  in 
other  matters. 


QUESTION  CXI. 

OF  DISSIMULATION  AND  HYPOCRISY. 
(In  Four  Articles.) 

In  due  sequence  we  must  consider  dissimulation  and  hypo- 
crisy. Under  this  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  all  dissimulation  is  a  sin  ?  (2)  Whether  hypo- 
crisy is  dissimulation  ?  (3)  Whether  it  is  opposed  to  truth  ? 
(4)  Whether  it  is  a  mortal  sin  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  all  dissimulation  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  this  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  not  all  dissimulation  is  a  sin. 
For  it  is  written  (Luke  xxiv.  28)  that  our  Lord  pretended 
(Douay, — made  as  though)  he  would  go  farther;  and  Ambrose 
in  his  book  on  the  Patriarchs  (De  Abraham,  i.)  says  of 
Abraham  that  he  spoke  craftily  to  his  servants,  when  he  said 
(Gen.  xxii.  5) :  /  and  the  boy  will  go  with  speed  as  far  as  yonder, 
and  after  we  have  worshipped,  will  return  to  you.  Now  to 
pretend  and  to  speak  craftily  savour  of  dissimulation :  and 
yet  it  is  not  to  be  said  that  there  was  sin  in  Christ  or  Abra- 
ham.    Therefore  not  all  dissimulation  is  a  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  No  sin  is  profitable.  But  according  to 
Jerome,  in  his  commentary  on  Gal.  ii.  n,  When  Peter 
(Vulg., — Cephas)  was  come  to  Antioch: — The  example  of  Jehu, 
king  of  Israel,  who  slew  the  priests  of  Baal,  pretending  that  he 
desired  to  worship  idols,  should  teach  us  that  dissimulation  is 
useful  and  sometimes  to  be  employed;  and  David  changed  his 
countenance  before  Achis,  king  of  Geth  (1  Kings  xxi.  13). 
Therefore  not  all  dissimulation  is  a  sin. 

99 


Q.  in.  Art.  i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  ioo 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Good  is  contrary  to  evil.  Therefore  if 
it  is  evil  to  simulate  good,  it  is  good  to  simulate  evil. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  It  is  written  in  condemnation  of  certain 
people  (Isa.  iii.  9) :  They  have  proclaimed  abroad  their  sin 
as  Sodom,  and  they  have  not  hid  it.  Now  it  pertains  to 
dissimulation  to  hide  one's  sin.  Therefore  it  is  repre- 
hensible sometimes  not  to  simulate.  But  it  is  never 
reprehensible  to  avoid  sin.  Therefore  dissimulation  is  not 
a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  A  gloss  on  Isa.  xvi.  14,  In  three  years,  etc., 
says :  Of  the  two  evils  it  is  less  to  sin  openly  than  to  simulate 
holiness.  But  to  sin  openly  is  always  a  sin:  Therefore  dis- 
simulation is  always  a  sin. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CIX.,  A.  3:  Q.  CX., 
A.  1),  it  belongs  to  the  virtue  of  truth  to  show  oneself  out- 
wardly by  outward  signs  to  be  such  as  one  is.  Now  out- 
ward signs  are  not  only  words,  but  also  deeds.  Accordingly 
just  as  it  is  contrary  to  truth  to  signify  by  words  something 
different  from  that  which  is  in  one's  mind,  so  also  is  it  con- 
trary to  truth  to  employ  signs  of  deeds  or  things  to  signify 
the  contrary  of  what  is  in  oneself,  and  this  is  what  is  properly 
denoted  by  dissimulation.  Consequently  dissimulation  is 
properly  a  lie  told  by  the  signs  of  outward  deeds.  Now  it 
matters  not  whether  one  lie  in  word  or  in  any  other  way, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  CX.,  A.  1,  Obj.  2).  Wherefore,  since 
every  lie  is  a  sin,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CX.,  A.  3),  it  follows 
that  also  all  dissimulation  is  a  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  Augustine  says  (De  QQ.  Evang.  ii.), 
To  pretend  is  not  always  a  lie  :  but  only  when  the  pretence 
has  no  signification,  then  it  is  a  lie.  When,  however,  our 
pretence  refers  to  some  signification,  there  is  no  lie,  but  a 
representation  of  the  truth.  And  he  cites  figures  of  speech 
as  an  example,  where  a  thing  is  pretended,  for  we  do  not 
mean  it  to  be  taken  literally  but  as  a  figure  of  something 
else  that  we  wish  to  say.  In  this  way  Our  Lord  pretended 
He  would  go  farther,  because  He  acted  as  if  wishing  to 
go  farther;  in  order  to  signify  something  figuratively  either 
because  He  was  far  from  their  faith,  according  to  Gregory 


ioi  HYPOCRISY  Q.  in.  Art.  i 

(Horn,  xxiii.  in  Ev.) ;  or,  as  Augustine  says  (De  QQ.  Evang. 
ii.),  because,  as  He  was  about  to  go  farther  away  from  them 
by  ascending  into  heaven,  He  was,  so  to  speak,  held  back  on 
earth  by  their  hospitality. 

Abraham  also  spoke  figuratively.  Wherefore  Ambrose 
(loc.  cit.)  says  that  Abraham  foretold  what  he  knew  not :  for 
he  intended  to  return  alone  after  sacrificing  his  son.  but 
by  his  mouth  the  Lord  expressed  what  He  was  about  to  do. 
It  is  evident  therefore  that  neither  dissembled. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Jerome  employs  the  term  simulation  in  a 
broad  sense  for  any  kind  of  pretence.  David's  change  of 
countenance  was  a  figurative  pretence,  as  a  gloss  observes 
in  commenting  on  the  title  of  Ps.  xxxiii.,  I  will  bless  the  Lord 
at  all  times.  There  is  no  need  to  excuse  Jehu's  dissimulation 
from  sin  or  He,  because  he  was  a  wicked  man,  since  he 
departed  not  from  the  idolatry  of  Jeroboam  (4  Kings  x. 
29,  31).  And  yet  he  is  praised  withal  and  received  an 
earthly  reward  from  God,  not  for  his  dissimulation,  but  for 
his  zeal  in  destroying  the  worship  of  Baal. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Some  say  that  no  one  may  pretend  to  be 
wicked,  because  no  one  pretends  to  be  wicked  by  doing  good 
deeds,  and  if  he  do  evil  deeds,  he  is  evil.  But  this  argument 
proves  nothing.  Because  a  man  might  pretend  to  be  evil, 
by  doing  what  is  not  evil  in  itself  but  has  some  appearance 
of  evil:  and  nevertheless  this  dissimulation  is  evil,  both 
because  it  is  a  lie,  and  because  it  gives  scandal;  and  although 
he  is  wicked  on  this  account,  yet  his  wickedness  is  not  the 
wickedness  he  simulates.  And  because  dissimulation  is 
evil  in  itself,  its  sinfulness  is  not  derived  from  the  thing 
simulated,  whether  this  be  good  or  evil. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Just  as  a  man  lies  when  he  signifies  by 
word  that  which  he  is  not,  yet  lies  not  when  he  refrains  from 
saying  what  he  is,  for  this  is  sometimes  lawful ;  so  also  does 
a  man  dissemble,  when  by  outward  signs  of  deeds  or  things 
he  signifies  that  which  he  is  not,  yet  he  dissembles  not  if  he 
omits  to  signify  what  he  is.  Hence  one  may  hide  one's 
sin  without  being  guilty  of  dissimulation.  It  is  thus  that 
we  must  understand  the  saying  of  Jerome  on   the  words 


Q.  in.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  102 

of  Isaias  (loc.  cit.),  that  the  second  plank  after  shipwreck 
is  to  hide  ones  sin,  lest,  to  wit,  others  be  scandalized 
thereby. 

Second  Article, 
whether  hypocrisy  is  the  same  as  dissimulation  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  hypocrisy  is  not  the  same  as 
dissimulation.  For  dissimulation  consists  in  lying  by  deeds. 
But  there  may  be  hypocrisy  in  showing  outwardly  what 
one  does  inwardly,  according  to  Matth.  vi.  2,  When  thou 
dost  an  alms-deed  sound  not  a  trumpet  before  thee,  as  the 
hypocrites  do.  Therefore  hypocrisy  is  not  the  same  as  dis- 
simulation. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Gregory  says  (Moral,  xxxi.  7) :  Some  there 
are  who  wear  the  habit  of  holiness,  yet  are  unable  to  attain 
the  merit  of  perfection.  We  must  by  no  means  deem  these 
to  have  joined  the  ranks  of  the  hypocrites,  since  it  is  one  thing 
to  sin  from  weakness,  and  another  to  sin  from  malice.  Now 
those  who  wear  the  habit  of  holiness,  without  attaining 
the  merit  of  perfection,  are  dissemblers,  since  the  outward 
habit  signifies  works  of  perfection.  Therefore  dissimulation 
is  not  the  same  as  hypocrisy. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Hypocrisy  consists  in  the  mere  intention. 
For  Our  Lord  says  of  hypocrites  (Matth.  xxiii.  5)  that  all 
their  works  they  do  for  to  be  seen  of  men  :  and  Gregory  says 
(Moral,  xxxi.  loc.  cit.)  that  they  never  consider  what  it  is  that 
they  do,  but  how  by  their  every  action  they  may  please  men. 
But  dissimulation  consists,  not  in  the  mere  intention,  but 
in  the  outward  action  :  wherefore  a  gloss  on  Job  xxxvi.  13, 
Dissemblers  and  crafty  men  prove  the  wrath  of  God,  says  that 
the  dissembler  simulates  one  thing  and  does  another ;  he 
pretends  chastity,  and  delights  in  lewdness,  he  makes  a  show 
of  poverty  and  fills  his  purse.  Therefore  hypocrisy  is  not 
the  same  as  dissimulation. 

On  the  contrary,  Isidore  says  (Etym.  x.)  :  '  Hypocrite  ' 
is  a  Greek  word  corresponding  to  the  Latin  '  simulator,'  for 


103  HYPOCRISY  Q.ui.Art.2 

whereas  he  is  evil  within,  he  shows  himself  outwardly  as  being 
good  ;  v7t6  denoting  falsehood,  and  Kpivis  judgment. 

I  answer  that.  As  Isidore  says  {ibid.),  the  word  hypocrite  is 
derived  from  the  appearance  of  those  who  come  on  to  the  stage 
with  a  disguised  face,  by  changing  the  colour  of  their  com- 
plexion, so  as  to  imitate  the  complexion  of  the  person  they 
simulate,  at  one  time  under  the  guise  of  a  man,  at  another 
under  the  guise  of  a  woman,  so  as  to  deceive  the  people  in 
their  acting.  Hence  Augustine  says  (De  Serm.  Dom.  ii.)  that 
just  as  hypocrites  by  simulating  other  persons  act  the  parts 
of  those  they  are  not  [since  he  that  acts  the  part  of  Agamemnon 
is  not  that  man  himself  but  pretends  to  be),  so  too  in  the 
Church  and  in  every  department  of  human  life,  whoever  wishes 
to  seem  what  he  is  not  is  a  hypocrite  :  for  he  pretends  to  be  just 
without  being  so  in  reality. 

We  must  conclude,  therefore,  that  hypocrisy  is  dissimula- 
tion, not,  however,  any  form  of  dissimulation,  but  only  when 
one  person  simulates  another,  as  when  a  sinner  simulates 
the  person  of  a  just  man. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  outward  deed  is  a  natural  sign  of  the 
intention.  Accordingly  when  a  man  does  good  works 
pertaining  by  their  genus  to  the  service  of  God,  and  seeks 
by  their  means  to  please,  not  God  but  man,  he  simulates 
a  right  intention  which  he  has  not.  Wherefore  Gregory  says 
(Moral,  xxxi.)  that  hypocrites  make  God's  interests  subservient 
to  worldly  purposes,  since  by  making  a  show  of  saintly  conduct 
they  seek,  not  to  turn  men  to  God,  but  to  draw  to  themselves 
the  applause  of  their  approval:  and  so  they  make  a  lying 
pretence  of  having  a  good  intention,  which  they  have 
not.  although  they  do  not  pretend  to  do  a  good  deed  without 
doing  it. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  habit  of  holiness,  for  instance  the 
religious  or  the  clerical  habit,  signifies  a  state  whereby  one 
is  bound  to  perform  works  of  perfection.  And  so  when  a 
man  puts  on  the  habit  of  holiness,  with  the  intention  of 
entering  the  state  of  perfection,  if  he  fail  through  weakness, 
he  is  not  a  dissembler  or  a  hypocrite,  because  he  is  not  bound 
to  disclose  his  sin  by  laying  aside  the  habit  of  holiness.     If, 


Q.  in.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA "  104 

however,  he  were  to  put  on  the  habit  of  holiness  in  order  to 
make  a  show  of  righteousness,  he  would  be  a  hypocrite  and 
a  dissembler. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  dissimulation,  as  in  a  lie,  there  are  two 
things:  one  by  way  of  sign,  the  other  by  way  of  thing 
signified.  Accordingly  the  evil  intention  in  hypocrisy  is 
considered  as  a  thing  signified,  which  does  not  tally  with 
the  sign:  and  the  outward  words,  or  deeds,  or  any  sensible 
objects  are  considered  in  every  dissimulation  and  lie  as  a  sign. 


Third  Article, 
whether  hypocrisy  is  contrary  to  the  virtue  of 

TRUTH  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  hypocrisy  is  not  contrary  to  the 
virtue  of  truth.  For  in  dissimulation  or  hypocrisy  there  is 
a  sign  and  a  thing  signified.  Now  with  regard  to  neither 
of  these  does  it  seem  to  be  opposed  to  any  special  virtue: 
for  a  hypocrite  simulates  any  virtue,  and  by  means  of  any 
virtuous  deeds,  such  as  fasting,  prayer  and  alms  deeds,  as 
stated  in  Matth.  vi.  1-18.  Therefore  hypocrisy  is  not  specially 
opposed  to  the  virtue  of  truth. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  All  dissimulation  seems  to  proceed  from 
guile,  wherefore  it  is  opposed  to  simplicity  Now  guile  is 
opposed  to  prudence  as  above  stated  (Q.  LV.,  A.  4). 
Therefore,  hypocrisy  which  is  dissimulation  is  not  opposed 
to  truth,  but  rather  to  prudence  or  simplicity. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  species  of  moral  acts  is  taken  from 
their  end.  Now  the  end  of  hypocrisy  is  the  acquisition  of 
gain  or  vainglory:  wherefore  a  gloss  on  Job  xxvii.  8,  What 
is  the  hope  of  the  hypocrite,  if  through  covetousness  he  take  by 
violence,  says :  A  hypocrite,  or,  as  the  Latin  has  it,  a  dissimu- 
lator, is  a  covetous  thief :  for  through  desire  of  being  honoured  for 
holiness,  though  guilty  of  wickedness,  he  steals  praise  for  a  life 
which  is  not  his.*    Therefore  since  covetousness  or  vainglory 

*  The  quotation  is  from  S.  Gregory's  Moralia,  Bk.  XVIII. 


105  HYPOCRISY  Q.ih.Art.3 

is  not  directly  opposed  to  truth,  it  seems  that  neither  is 
hypocrisy  or  dissimulation. 

On  the  contrary,  All  dissimulation  is  a  lie,  as  stated  above 
(A.  i).  Now  a  lie  is  directly  opposed  to  truth.  Therefore 
dissimulation  or  hypocrisy  is  also. 

/  answer  that,  According  to  the  Philosopher  (M  eta  ph.  text. 
13,  24,  x.),  contrariety  is  opposition  as  regards  form,  i.e.  the 
specific  form.  Accordingly  we  must  reply  that  dissimulation 
or  hypocrisy  may  be  opposed  to  a  virtue  in  two  ways,  in  one 
way  directly,  in  another  way  indirectly.  Its  direct  opposi- 
tion or  contrariety  is  to  be  considered  with  regard  to  the 
very  species  of  the  act,  and  this  species  depends  on  that 
act's  proper  object.  Wherefore  since  hypocrisy  is  a  kind 
of  dissimulation,  whereby  a  man  simulates  a  character 
which  is  not  his,  as  stated  in  the  preceding  article,  it  follows 
that  it  is  directly  opposed  to  truth,  whereby  a  man  shows 
himself  in  life  and  speech  to  be  what  he  is,  as  stated  in 
Ethic,  iv.  7. 

The  indirect  opposition  or  contrariety  of  hypocrisy  may 
be  considered  in  relation  to  any  accident,  for  instance  a 
remote  end,  or  an  instrument  of  action,  or  anything  else  of 
that  kind. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  hypocrite  in  simulating  a  virtue  regards 
it  as  his  end,  not  in  respect  of  its  existence,  as  though  he 
wished  to  have  it,  but  in  respect  of  appearance,  since  he 
wishes  to  seem  to  have  it.  Hence  his  hypocrisy  is  not 
opposed  to  that  virtue,  but  to  truth,  inasmuch  as  he  wishes 
to  deceive  men  with  regard  to  that  virtue.  And  he  performs 
acts  of  that  virtue,  not  as  intending  them  for  their  own  sake, 
but  instrumentally,  as  signs  of  that  virtue,  wherefore  his 
hypocrisy  has  not,  on  that  account,  a  direct  opposition  to 
that  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  stated  above  (Q.  LV.,  AA.  3,  4,  5),  the 
vice  directly  opposed  to  prudence  is  cunning,  to  which  it 
belongs  to  discover  ways  of  achieving  a  purpose,  that  are 
apparent  and  not  real:  while  it  accomplishes  that  purpose, 
by  guile  in  words,  and  by  fraud  in  deeds :  and  it  stands  in 
relation  to  prudence,  as  guile  and  fraud  to  simplicity.     Now 


Q.  in.  Art.  4    THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  106 

guile  and  fraud  are  directed  chiefly  to  deception,  and  some- 
times secondarily  to  injury.  Wherefore  it  belongs  directly 
to  simplicity  to  guard  oneself  from  deception,  and  in  this 
way  the  virtue  of  simplicity  is  the  same  as  the  virtue  of 
truth  as  stated  above  (0.  CIX.,  A.  2,  ad  4).  There  is,  how- 
ever, a  mere  logical  difference  between  them,  because  by 
truth  we  mean  the  concordance  between  sign  and  thing 
signified,  while  simplicity  indicates  that  one  does  not  tend 
to  different  things,  by  intending  one  thing  inwardly,  and 
pretending  another  outwardly. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Gain  or  glory  is  the  remote  end  of  the  dis- 
sembler as  also  of  the  liar.  Hence  it  does  not  take  its  species 
from  this  end,  but  from  the  proximate  end,  which  is  to  show 
oneself  other  than  one  is.  Wherefore  it  sometimes  happens 
to  a  man  to  pretend  great  things  of  himself,  for  no  further 
purpose  than  the  mere  lust  of  hypocrisy,  as  the  Philosopher 
says  (Ethic,  iv.  7),  and  as  also  we  have  said  above  with 
regard  to  lying  (Q.  CX.,  A.  2). 

Fourth  Article. 
whether  hypocrisy  is  always  a  mortal  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  hypocrisy  is  always  a  mortal 
sin.  For  Jerome  says  on  Isa.  xvi.  14:  Of  the  two  evils  it  is  less 
to  sin  openly  than  to  simulate  holiness:  and  a  gloss  on  Job  i.  21,* 
As  it  hath  pleased  the  Lord,  etc.,  says  that  pretended  justice  is 
no  justice,  but  a  twofold  sin:  and  again  a  gloss  on  Lament,  iv.  6, 
The  iniquity  .  .  .  of  My  people  is  made  greater  than  the  sin  of 
Sodom,  savs :  He  deplores  the  sins  of  the  soul  that  falls  into 
hypocrisy,  which  is  a  greater  iniquity  than  the  sin  of  Sodom. 
Now  the  sins  of  Sodom  are  mortal  sin.  Therefore  hypocrisy 
is  always  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Gregory  says  (Moral,  xxxi.  8)  that  hypo- 
crites sin  out  of  malice.  But  this  is  most  grievous,  for  it 
pertains  to  the  sin  against  the  Holy  Ghost.  Therefore  a 
hypocrite  always  sins  mortally. 

*  S.  Augustine,  on  Ps.  lxiii.  7. 


107  HYPOCRISY  Qui.  Art.  4 

Obj.  3.  Further,  No  one  deserves  the  anger  of  God  and 
exclusion  from  seeing  God,  save  on  account  of  mortal  sin. 
Now  the  anger  of  God  is  deserved  through  hypocrisy  accord- 
ing to  Job  xxxvi.  13,  Dissemblers  and  crafty  men  prove  the 
wrath  of  God :  and  the  hypocrite  is  excluded  from  seeing 
God,  according  to  Job  xiii.  16,  No  hypocrite  shall  come 
before  His  presence.  Therefore  hypocrisy  is  always  a 
mortal  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Hypocrisy  is  lying  by  deed  since  it  is  a 
kind  of  dissimulation.  But  it  is  not  always  a  mortal  sin  to 
lie  by  deed.     Neither  therefore  is  all  hypocrisy  a  mortal  sin. 

Further,  The  intention  of  a  hypocrite  is  to  appear  to 
be  good.  But  this  is  not  contrary  to  charity.  Therefore 
hypocrisy  is  not  of  itself  a  mortal  sin. 

Further,  Hypocrisy  is  born  of  vainglory,  as  Gregory  says 
(Moral,  xxxi.  17).  But  vainglory  is  not  always  a  mortal 
sin.     Neither  therefore  is  hypocrisy. 

/  answer  that,  There  are  two  things  in  hypocrisy,  lack  of 
holiness,  and  simulation  thereof.  Accordingly  if  by  a 
hypocrite  we  mean  a  person  whose  intention  is  directed  to 
both  the  above,  one,  namely,  who  cares  not  to  be  holy  but 
only  to  appear  so,  in  which  sense  Sacred  Scripture  is  wont 
to  use  the  term,  it  is  evident  that  hypocrisy  is  a  mortal  sin: 
for  no  one  is  entirely  deprived  of  holiness  save  through 
mortal  sin.  But  if  by  a  hypocrite  we  mean  one  who  intends 
to  simulate  holiness,  which  he  lacks  through  mortal  sin, 
then,  although  he  is  in  mortal  sin,  whereby  he  is  deprived 
of  holiness,  yet,  in  his  case,  the  dissimulation  itself  is  not 
always  a  mortal  sin,  but  sometimes  a  venial  sin.  This  will 
depend  on  the  end  in  view;  for  if  this  be  contrary  to  the  love 
of  God  or  of  his  neighbour,  it  will  be  a  mortal  sin :  for  instance 
if  he  were  to  simulate  holiness  in  order  to  disseminate  false 
doctrine,  or  that  he  may  obtain  ecclesiastical  preferment, 
though  unworthy,  or  that  he  may  obtain  any  temporal  good 
in  which  he  fixes  his  end.  If,  however,  the  end  intended  be 
not  contrary  to  charity,  it  will  be  a  venial  sin,  as  for  instance 
when  a  man  takes  pleasure  in  the  pretence  itself:  of  such 
a  man  it  is  said  in  Ethic,  iv.  7  that  he  would  seem  to  be 


Q.  in.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  108 

vain  rather  than  evil;  for  the  same  applies  to  simulation  as 
to  a  lie. 

It  happens  also  sometimes  that  a  man  simulates  the 
perfection  of  holiness  which  is  not  necessary  for  spiritual 
welfare.  Simulation  of  this  kind  is  neither  a  mortal  sin 
always,  nor  is  it  always  associated  with  mortal  sin. 

This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Objections. 


QUESTION  CXII. 

OF  BOASTING. 

(In   Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  boasting  and  irony,  which  are  parts 
of  lying  according  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  iv.  7).  Under 
the  first  head,  namely,  boasting,  there  are  two  points  of 
inquiry:  (1)  To  which  virtue  is  it  opposed  ?  (2)  Whether 
it  is  a  mortal  sin  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  boasting  is  opposed  to  the  virtue  of 

TRUTH  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  A  Hide  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  boasting  is  not  opposed  to 
the  virtue  of  truth.  For  lying  is  opposed  to  truth.  But 
it  is  possible  to  boast  even  without  lying,  as  when  a  man 
makes  a  show  of  his  own  excellence.  Thus  it  is  written 
(Esther  i.  3,  4)  that  Assuerus  made  a  great  feast  .  .  .  that  he 
might  show  the  riches  of  the  glory  and  of  his  kingdom,  and  the 
greatness  and  boasting  of  his  power.  Therefore  boasting  is 
not  opposed  to  the  virtue  of  truth. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Boasting  is  reckoned  by  Gregory  (Moral. 
xxiii.  4)  to  be  one  of  the  four  species  of  pride,  when,  to  wit, 
a  man  boasts  of  having  what  he  has  not.  Hence  it  is  written 
(Jerem.  xlviii.  29,  30) :  We  have  heard  the  pride  of  Moab,  he 
is  exceeding  proud:  his  haughtiness,  and  his  arrogancy,  and 
his  pride,  and  the  loftiness  of  his  heart.  I  know,  saith  the 
Lord,  his  boasting,  and  that  the  strength  thereof  is  not  according 
to  it.  Moreover,  Gregory  says  (Moral,  xxxi.  7)  that  boasting 
arises    from    vainglory.     Now    pride    and    vainglory    are 

109 


Q.  ii2.  Art.  i    THE  *' SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  no 

opposed  to  the  virtue  of  humility.     Therefore  boasting  is 
opposed,  not  to  truth,  but  to  humility. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Boasting  seems  to  be  occasioned  by 
riches;  wherefore  it  is  written  (Wis.  v.  8):  What  hath  pride 
■profited  us  ?  or  what  advantage  hath  the  boasting  of  riches 
brought  us  ?  Now  excess  of  riches  seems  to  belong  to  the  sin 
of  covetousness,  which  is  opposed  to  justice  or  liberality. 
Therefore  boasting  is  not  opposed  to  truth. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  ii.  7,  iv.  7), 
that  boasting  is  opposed  to  truth. 

/  answer  that,  Jactantia  (boasting)  seems  properly  to 
denote  the  uplifting  of  self  by  words :  since  if  a  man  wishes 
to*  throw  (jactare)  a  thing  far  away,  he  lifts  it  up  high.  And 
to  uplift  oneself,  properly  speaking,  is  to  talk  of  oneself 
above  oneself.*  This  happens  in  two  ways.  For  some- 
times a  man  speaks  of  himself,  not  above  what  he  is  in  him- 
self, but  above  that  which  he  is  esteemed  by  men  to  be: 
and  this  the  Apostle  declines  to  do  when  he  says  (2  Cor.  xii.  6) : 
I  forbear,  lest  any  man  should  think  of  me  above  that  which 
he  seeth  in  me,  or  anything  he  heareth  of  me.  In  another  way 
a  man  uplifts  himself  in  words,  by  speaking  of  himself  above 
that  which  he  is  in  reality.  And  since  we  should  judge  of 
things  as  they  are  in  themselves,  rather  than  as  others  deem 
them  to  be,  it  follows  that  boasting  denotes  more  properly 
the  uplifting  of  self  above  what  one  is  in  oneself,  than  the 
uplifting  of  self  above  what  others  think  of  one :  although  in 
either  case  it  may  be  called  boasting.  Hence  boasting 
properly  so  called  is  opposed  to  truth  by  way  of  excess. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  argument  takes  boasting  as  exceeding 
men's  opinion. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  sin  of  boasting  may  be  considered  in 
two  ways.  First,  with  regard  to  the  species  of  the  act,  and 
thus  it  is  opposed  to  truth,  as  stated  (in  the  body  of  the 
article  and  Q.  CX.,  A.  2).  Secondly,  with  regard  to  its 
cause,  from  which  more  frequently  though  not  always  it 
arises :  and  thus  it  proceeds  from  pride  as  its  inwardly  moving 
and  impelling  cause.  For  when  a  man  is  uplifted  inwardly 
*  Or  tall-talking,  as  we  should  say  in  English. 


Ill  BOASTING  Q.i  12.  Art.  i 

by  arrogance,  it  often  results  that  outwardly  he  boasts  of 
great  things  about  himself;  though  sometimes  a  man  takes 
to  boasting,  not  from  arrogance,  but  from  some  kind  of 
vanity,  and  delights  therein,  because  he  is  a  boaster  by  habit. 
Hence  arrogance,  which  is  an  uplifting  of  self  above  oneself, 
is  a  kind  of  pride ;  yet  it  is  not  the  same  as  boasting,  but  is 
very  often  its  cause.  For  this  reason  Gregory  reckons 
boasting  among  the  species  of  pride.  Moreover,  the  boaster 
frequently  aims  at  obtaining  glory  through  his  boasting, 
and  so,  according  to  Gregory,  it  arises  from  vainglory  con- 
sidered as  its  end. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Wealth  also  causes  boasting,  in  two  ways. 
First,  as  an  occasional  cause,  inasmuch  as  a  man  prides  him- 
self on  his  riches.  Hence  (Prov.  viii.  18)  riches  are  signifi- 
cantly described  as  proud  (Douay, — glorious).  Secondly, 
as  being  the  end  of  boasting,  since  according  to  Ethic,  iv.  7 
some  boast,  not  only  for  the  sake  of  glory,  but  also  for  the 
sake  of  gain.  Such  people  invent  stories  about  themselves, 
so  as  to  make  profit  thereby ;  for  instance,  they  pretend  to 
be  skilled  in  medicine,  wisdom,  or  divination. 


Second  Article, 
whether  boasting  is  a  mortal  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  boasting  is  a  mortal  sin.  For 
it  is  written  (Prov.  xxviii.  25) :  He  that  boasteth,  and  puffeth 
himself,  stirreth  up  quarrels.  Now  it  is  a  mortal  sin  to  stir 
up  quarrels,  since  God  hates  those  that  sow  discord,  accord- 
ing to  Prov.  vi.  19.     Therefore  boasting  is  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Whatever  is  forbidden  in  God's  law  is  a 
mortal  sin.  Now  a  gloss  on  Ecclus.  vi.  2,  Extol  not  thyself 
in  the  thoughts  of  thy  soul,  says :  This  is  a  prohibition  of  boast- 
ing and  pride.     Therefore  boasting  is  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Boasting  is  a  kind  of  lie.  But  it  is  neither 
an  officious  nor  a  jocose  lie.  This  is  evident  from  the  end 
of  lying;  for  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  7),  the 
boaster  pretends  to  something  greater  than  he  is,  sometimes  for 


Q.  ii2.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  112 

no  further  purpose,  sometimes  for  the  sake  of  glory  or  honour, 
sometimes  for  the  sake  of  money.  Thus  it  is  evident  that  it 
is  neither  an  officious  nor  a  jocose  lie,  and  consequently  it 
must  be  a  mischievous  lie.  Therefore  seemingly  it  is  always 
a  mortal  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Boasting  arises  from  vainglory,  according 
to  Gregory  {Moral,  xxxi.  17).  Now  vainglory  is  not  always 
a  mortal  sin,  but  is  sometimes  a  venial  sin  which  only  the 
very  perfect  avoid.  For  Gregory  says  {Moral,  viii.  30)  that 
it  belongs  to  the  very  perfect,  by  outward  deeds  so  to  seek  the 
glory  of  their  author,  that  they  are  not  inwardly  uplifted  by  the 
praise  awarded  them.  Therefore  boasting  is  not  always  a 
mortal  sin. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CX.,  A.  4),  a  mortal  sin 
is  one  that  is  contrary  to  charity.  Accordingly  boasting 
may  be  considered  in  two  ways.  First,  in  itself,  as  a  he, 
and  thus  it  is  sometimes  a  mortal,  and  sometimes  a  venial, 
sin.  It  will  be  a  mortal  sin  when  a  man  boasts  of  that  which 
is  contrary  to  God's  glory — thus  it  is  said  in  the  person  of  the 
king  of  Tyre  (Ezech.  xxviii.  2) :  Thy  heart  is  lifted  up,  and 
thou  hast  said :  I  am  God — or  contrary  to  the  love  of  our 
neighbour,  as  when  a  man  while  boasting  of  himself  breaks 
out  into  invectives  against  others,  as  told  of  the  Pharisee 
who  said  (Luke  xviii.  11) :  /  am  not  as  the  rest  of  men,  extor- 
tioners, unjust,  adulterers,  as  also  is  this  publican.  Some- 
times it  is  a  venial  sin,  when,  to  wit,  a  man  boasts  of  things 
that  are  against  neither  God  nor  his  neighbour. 

Secondly,  it  may  be  considered  with  regard  to  its  cause, 
namely,  pride,  or  the  desire  of  gain  or  of  vainglory :  and  then 
if  it  proceeds  from  pride  or  from  such  vainglory  as  is  a 
mortal  sin,  then  the  boasting  will  also  be  a  mortal  sin :  other- 
wise it  will  be  a  venial  sin.  Sometimes,  however,  a  man 
breaks  out  into  boasting  through  desire  of  gain,  and  for  this 
very  reason  he  would  seem  to  be  aiming  at  the  deception  and 
injury  of  his  neighbour:  wherefore  boasting  of  this  kind  is 
more  likely  to  be  a  mortal  sin.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic,  iv.  7)  that  a  man  who  boasts  for  the  sake  of  gain,  is  viler 
than  one  who  boasts  for  the  sake  of  glory  or  honour.     Yet  it  is 


113  BOASTING  Q.  112.  Art.  2 

not  always  a  mortal  sin  because  the  gain  may  be  such  as  not 
to  injure  another  man. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  To  boast  in  order  to  stir  up  quarrels  is  a 
mortal  sin.  But  it  happens  sometimes  that  boasts  are  the 
cause  of  quarrels,  not  intentionally  but  accidentally:  and 
consequently  boasting  will  not  be  a  mortal  sin  on  that 
account. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  gloss  speaks  of  boasting  as  arising 
from  pride  that  is  a  mortal  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Boasting  does  not  always  involve  a  mis- 
chievous lie,  but  only  where  it  is  contrary  to  the  love  of 
God  or  our  neighbour,  either  in  itself  or  in  its  cause.  That 
a  man  boast,  through  mere  pleasure  in  boasting,  is  an 
inane  thing  to  do,  as  the  Philosopher  remarks  {Ethic,  iv.  7) : 
wherefore  it  amounts  to  a  jocose  lie.  Unless  perchance  he 
were  to  prefer  this  to  the  love  of  God,  so  as  to  contemn 
God's  commandments  for  the  sake  of  boasting:  for  then  it 
would  be  against  the  charity  of  God,  in  Whom  alone  ought 
our  mind  to  rest  as  in  its  last  end. 

To  boast  for  the  sake  of  glory  or  gain  seems  to  involve 
an  officious  lie:  provided  it  be  done  without  injury  to  others, 
for  then  it  would  at  once  become  a  mischievous  lie. 


II.  ii.  4 


QUESTION  CXIIL 

OF  IRONY* 

(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  irony,  under  which  head  there  are 
two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  irony  is  a  sin  ?  (2)  Of 
its  comparison  with  boasting. 

First  Article, 
whether  irony  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  irony,  which  consists  in  be- 
littling oneself,  is  not  a  sin.  For  no  sin  arises  from  one's 
being  strengthened  by  God :  and  yet  this  leads  one  to  belittle 
oneself,  according  to  Prov.  xxx.  1,  2,  The  vision  which  the 
man  spoke,  with  whom  is  God,  and  who  being  strengthened  by 
God,  abiding  with  him,  said,  I  am  the  most  foolish  of  men. 
Also  it  is  written  (Amos  vii.  14) :  Amos  answered  ...  7  am 
not  a  prophet.  Therefore  irony,  whereby  a  man  belittles 
himself  in  words,  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Gregory  says  in  a  letter  to  Augustine, 
bishop  of  the  English  (Regist.  xii.) :  It  is  the  mark  of  a  well- 
disposed  mind  to  acknowledge  one's  fault  when  one  is  not 
guilty.  But  all  sin  is  inconsistent  with  a  well-disposed 
mind.     Therefore  irony  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  is  not  a  sin  to  shun  pride.  But  some 
belittle  themselves  in  words,  so  as  to  avoid  pride,  according  to 
the  Philosopher  [Ethic,  iv.  7).     Therefore  irony  is  not  a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Verb.  Apost.,  Serm. 

*  Iron}'  here  must  be  given  the  signification  of  the  Greek  slpu>via, 
whence  it  is  derived: — dissimulation  of  one's  own  good  points. 

114 


115  IRONY  Q.  113.  Art.  i 

xxix.):  If  thou  liest  on  account  of  humility,  if  thou  wert  not 
a  sinner  before  lying,  thou  hast  become  one  by  lying. 

I  answer  that,  To  speak  so  as  to  belittle  oneself  may  occur 
in  two  ways.  First  so  as  to  safeguard  truth,  as  when  a 
man  conceals  the  greater  things  in  himself,  but  discovers 
and  asserts  lesser  things  of  himself  the  presence  of  which 
in  himself  he  perceives.  To  belittle  oneself  in  this  way  does 
not  belong  to  irony,  nor  is  it  a  sin  in  respect  of  its  genus, 
except  through  corruption  of  one  of  its  circumstances. 
Secondly,  a  person  belittles  himself  by  forsaking  the  truth, 
for  instance  by  ascribing  to  himself  something  mean  the 
existence  of  which  in  himself  he  does  not  perceive,  or  by 
denying  something  great  of  himself,  which  nevertheless  he 
perceives  himself  to  possess:  this  pertains  to  irony,  and  is 
always  a  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  There  is  a  twofold  wisdom  and  a  twofold 
folly.  For  there  is  a  wisdom  according  to  God,  which  has 
human  or  worldly  folly  annexed  to  it,  according  to  1  Cor. 
iii.  18,  If  any  man  among  you  seem  to  be  wise  in  this  world,  let 
him  become  a  fool  that  he  may  be  wise.  But  there  is  another 
wisdom  that  is  worldly,  which  as  the  same  text  goes  on  to 
say,  is  foolishness  with  God.  Accordingly,  he  that  is  streng- 
thened by  God  acknowledges  himself  to  be  most  foolish  in 
the  estimation  of  men,  because,  to  wit,  he  despises  human 
things,  which  human  wisdom  seeks.  Hence  the  text  quoted 
continues,  and  the  wisdom  of  men  is  not  with  me,  and  farther 
on,  and*  I  have  known  the  science  of  the  saints. 

It  may  also  be  replied  that  the  wisdom  of  men  is  that  which 
is  acquired  by  human  reason,  while  the  wisdom  of  the  saints 
is  that  which  is  received  by  divine  inspiration. 

Amos  denied  that  he  was  a  prophet  by  birth,  sinee,  to  wit, 
he  was  not  of  the  race  of  prophets :  hence  the  text  goes  on, 
nor  am  I  the  son  of  a  prophet. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  belongs  to  a  well-disposed  mind  that  a 

man  tend  to  perfect  righteousness,  and  consequently  deem 

himself    guilty,    not    only    if    he   fall   short    of   common 

righteousness,  which  is  truly  a  sin,  but  also  if  he  fall  short  of 

*  Vulg., — and  I  have  not  known  the  science  of  the  saints. 


Q.  n3.  Art.  2    THE  *' SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  116 

perfect  righteousness,  which  sometimes  is  not  a  sin.  But 
he  does  not  call  sinful  that  which  he  does  not  acknowledge 
to  be  sinful:  which  wo  aid  be  a  lie  of  irony. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  A  man  should  not  commit  one  sin  in  order 
to  avoid  another :  and  so  he  ought  not  to  lie  in  any  way  at  all 
in  order  to  avoid  pride.  Hence  Augustine  says  {Tract,  xliii. 
in  Joan.) :  Shun  not  arrogance  so  as  to  forsake  truth  :  and 
Gregory  says  (Moral,  xxvi.  3)  that  it  is  a  reckless  humility 
that  entangles  itself  with  lies. 


Second  Article, 
whether  irony  is  a  less  grievous  sin  than  boasting  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  irony  is  not  a  less  grievous  sin 
than  boasting.  For  each  of  them  is  a  sin  through  forsaking 
truth,  which  is  a  kind  of  equality.  But  one  does  not  forsake 
truth  by  exceeding  it  any  more  than  by  diminishing  it. 
Therefore  irony  is  not  a  less  grievous  sin  than  boasting. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  According  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  7), 
irony  sometimes  is  boasting.  But  boasting  is  not  irony. 
Therefore  irony  is  not  a  less  grievous  sin  than  boasting. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  is  written  (Prov.  xxvi.  25) :  When 
he  shall  speak  low,  trust  him  not :  because  there  are  seven  mis- 
chiefs in  his  heart.  Now  it  belongs  to  irony  to  speak  low. 
Therefore  it  contains  a  manifold  wickedness. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  7) :  Those 
who  speak  with  irony  and  belittle  themselves  are  more  gracious, 
seemingly,  in  their  manners. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CX.,  AA.  2,  4),  one  lie 
is  more  grievous  than  another,  sometimes  on  account  of  the 
matter  which  it  is  about — thus  a  lie  about  a  matter  of  religious 
doctrine  is  most  grievous — and  sometimes  on  account  of  the 
motive  for  sinning;  thus  a  mischievous  lie  is  more  grievous 
than  an  officious  or  jocose  lie.  Now  irony  and  boasting  lie 
about  the  same  matter,  either  by  words,  or  by  any  other 
outward  signs,  namely,  about  matters  affecting  the  person : 
so  that  in  this  respect  they  are  equal. 


ii7  IRONY  Q.  113.  Art.  2 

But  for  the  most  part  boasting  proceeds  from  a  viler  motive, 
namely,  the  desire  of  gain  or  honour:  whereas  irony  arises 
from  a  man's  averseness,  albeit  inordinate,  to  be  disagreeable 
to  others  by  uplifting  himself:  and  in  this  respect  the  Philo- 
sopher says  (loc.  cit.)  that  boasting  is  a  more  grievous  sin  than 
irony. 

Sometimes,  however,  it  happens  that  a  man  belittles  him- 
self for  some  other  motive,  for  instance  that  he  may  deceive 
cunningly :  and  then  irony  is  more  grievous. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  argument  applies  to  irony  and  boast- 
ing, according  as  a  lie  is  considered  to  be  grievous  in  itself  or 
on  account  of  its  matter :  for  it  has  been  said  that  in  this  way 
they  are  equal. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Excellence  is  twofold:  one  is  in  temporal, 
the  other  in  spiritual  things.  Now  it  happens  at  times  that 
a  person,  by  outward  words  or  signs,  pretends  to  be  lacking 
in  external  things,  for  instance  by  wearing  shabby  clothes, 
or  by  doing  something  of  the  kind,  and  that  he  intends  by  so 
doing  to  make  a  show  of  some  spiritual  excellence.  Thus 
Our  Lord  said  of  certain  men  (Matth.  vi.  16)  that  they  dis- 
figure their  faces  that  they  may  appear  unto  men  to  fast. 
Wherefore  such  persons  are  guilty  of  both  vices,  irony  and 
boasting,  although  in  different  respects,  and  for  this  reason 
they  sin  more  grievously.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic,  iv.  7)  that  it  is  the  practice  of  boasters  both  to  make 
overmuch  of  themselves,  and  to  make  very  little  of  themselves  : 
and  for  the  same  reason  it  is  related  of  Augustine  that  he 
was  unwilling  to  possess  clothes  that  were  either  too  costly 
or  too  shabby,  because  by  both  do  men  seek  glory. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  According  to  the  words  of  Ecclus.  xix.  23, 
There  is  one  that  humbleth  himself  wickedly,  and  his  interior 
is  full  of  deceit,  and  it  is  in  this  sense  that  Solomon  speaks 
of  the  man  who,  through  deceitful  humility,  speaks  low 
wickedly. 


QUESTION  CXIV. 

OF  THE  FRIENDLINESS  WHICH  IS  CALLED  AFFABILITY. 

(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  friendliness  which  is  called  affa- 
bility, and  the  opposite  vices  which  are  flattery  and  quarrel- 
ling. Concerning  friendliness  or  affability,  there  are  two 
points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  it  is  a  special  virtue  ? 
(2)  Whether  it  is  a  part  of  justice  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  friendliness  is  a  special  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  friendliness  is  not  a  special 
virtue.  For  the  Philosopher  saj^s  (Ethic,  viii.  3)  that  the 
perfect  friendship  is  that  which  is  on  account  of  virtue.  Now 
any  virtue  is  the  cause  of  friendship:  since  the  good  is  lovable 
to  all,  as  Dionysius  states  (Div.  Norn.  iv.).  Therefore 
friendliness  is  not  a  special  virtue,  but  a  consequence  of 
every  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  6)  of 
this  kind  of  friend  that  he  takes  everything  in  a  right  manner 
from  those  he  loves  not  and  are  not  his  friends.  Now  it  seems 
to  pertain  to  simulation  that  a  person  should  show  signs  of 
friendship  to  those  whom  he  loves  not,  and  this  is  incom- 
patible with  virtue.  Therefore  this  kind  of  friendliness  is 
not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Virtue  observes  the  mean,  according  as 
a  wise  man  decides  (Ethic,  ii.  6).  Now  it  is  written  (Eccles. 
vii.  5) :  The  heart  of  the  wise  is  where  there  is  mourning,  and 

118 


H9  FRIENDLINESS  Q.  n4.  Art.  i 

the  heart  of  fools  where  there  is  mirth:  wherefore  it  belongs 
to  a  virtuous  man  to  be  most  wary  of  pleasure  {Ethic,  ii.  9). 
Now  this  kind  of  friendship,  according  to  the  Philosopher 
(Ethic,  iv.  6),  is  essentially  desirous  of  sharing  pleasures,  but 
fears  to  give  pain.  Therefore  this  kind  of  friendliness  is  not 
a  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  The  precepts  of  the  law  are  about  acts 
of  virtue.  Now  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  iv.  7) :  Make  thyself 
affable  to  the  congregation  of  the  poor.  Therefore  affability, 
which  is  what  we  mean  by  friendship,  is  a  special  virtue. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CIX.,  A.  2:  I. -II., 
Q.  LV.,  A.  3),  since  virtue  is  directed  to  good,  wherever  there 
is  a  special  kind  of  good,  there  must  needs  be  a  special  kind 
of  virtue.  Now  good  consists  in  order,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CIX.,  A.  2).  And  it  behoves  man  to  be  maintained  in  a 
becoming  order  towards  other  men  as  regards  their  mutual 
relations  with  one  another,  in  point  of  both  deeds  and  words, 
so  that  they  behave  towards  one  another  in  a  becoming 
manner.  Hence  the  need  of  a  special  virtue  that  maintains 
the  becomingness  of  this  order:  and  this  virtue  is  called 
friendliness. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  Philosopher  speaks  of  a  twofold 
friendship  in  his  Ethics.  One  consists  chiefly  in  the  affec- 
tion whereby  one  man  loves  another  and  may  result  from 
any  virtue.  We  have  stated  above,  in  treating  of  charity 
(Q.  XXIII. ,  A.  1,  A.  3, adi:  QQ.  XXV.,  XXVI.),  what  things 
belong  to  this  kind  of  friendship.  But  he  mentions  another 
friendliness,  which  consists  merely  in  outward  words  or  deeds; 
this  has  not  the  perfect  nature  of  friendship,  but  bears  a 
certain  likeness  thereto,  in  so  far  as  a  man  behaves  in  a 
becoming  manner  towards  those  with  whom  he  is  in 
contact. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Every  man  is  naturally  every  man's 
friend  by  a  certain  general  love;  even  so  it  is  written  (Ecclus. 
xiii.  19)  that  every  beast  loveth  its  like.  This  love  is  signified 
by  signs  of  friendship,  which  we  show  outwardly  by  words 
or  deeds,  even  to  those  who  are  strangers  or  unknown  to  us. 
Hence  there  is  no  dissimulation  in  this :  because  we  do  not 


Q.  114.  Art.  i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  120 

show  them  signs  of  perfect  friendship,  for  we  do  not  treat 
strangers  with  the  same  intimacy  as  those  who  are  united 
to  us  by  special  friendship. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  When  it  is  said  that  the  heart  of  the  wise 
is  where  there  is  mourning  it  is  not  that  he  may  bring  sorrow 
to  his  neighbour,  for  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  xiv.  15):  //, 
because  of  thy  meat,  thy  brother  be  grieved,  thou  walkest  not 
now  according  to  charity  :  but  that  he  may  bring  consolation 
to  the  sorrowful,  according  to  Ecclus.  vii.  38,  Be  not  wanting 
in  comforting  them  that  weep,  and  walk  with  them  that  mourn. 
Again,  the  heart  oj  fools  is  where  there  is  mirth,  not  that  they 
may  gladden  others,  but  that  they  may  enjoy  others'  gladness. 
Accordingly,  it  belongs  to  the  wise  man  to  share  his  pleasures 
with  those  among  whom  he  dwells,  not  lustful  pleasures, 
which  virtue  shuns,  but  honest  pleasures,  according  to 
Ps.  cxxxii.  1,  Behold  how  good  and  how  pleasant  it  is  for 
brethren  to  dwell  together  in  unity. 

Nevertheless,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  6),  for  the 
sake  of  some  good  that  will  result,  or  in  order  to  avoid 
some  evil,  the  virtuous  man  will  sometimes  not  shrink  from 
bringing  sorrow  to  those  among  whom  he  lives.  Hence  the 
Apostle  says  (2  Cor.  vii.  8) :  Although  I  made  you  sorrowful 
by  my  epistle,  I  do  not  repent,  and  farther  on  (verse  9),  I  am 
glad  ;  not  because  you  were  made  sorrowful,  but  because  you 
were  made  sorrowful  unto  penance.  For  this  reason  we  should 
not  show  a  cheerful  face  to  those  who  are  given  to  sin,  in 
order  that  we  may  please  them,  lest  we  seem  to  consent  to 
their  sin,  and  in  a  way  encourage  them  to  sin  further. 
Hence  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  vii.  26) :  Hast  thou  daughters  ? 
Have  a  care  of  their  body,  and  show  not  thy  countenance  gay 
towards  them. 

Second  Article, 
whether  this  kind  of  friendship  is  a  part  of  justice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  I.  It  seems  that  this  kind  of  friendship  is  not 
a  part  of  justice.  For  justice  consists  in  giving  another 
man  his  due.     But  this  virtue  does  not  consist  in  doing 


121  FRIENDLINESS  Q.h4.Art.2 

that,  but  in  behaving  agreeably  towards  those  among  whom 
we  live.     Therefore  this  virtue  is  not  a  part  of  justice. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  According  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  6), 
this  virtue  is  concerned  about  the  joys  and  sorrows  of  those 
who  dwell  in  fellowship.  Now  it  belongs  to  temperance 
to  moderate  the  greatest  pleasures,  as  stated  above  (I.-IL, 
Q.  LX.,  A.  5:  Q.  LXI.,  A.  3).  Therefore  this  virtue  is  a 
part  of  temperance  rather  than  of  justice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  To  give  equal  things  to  those  who  are 
unequal  is  contrary  to  justice,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LIX., 
AA.  1,  2).  Now,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  6), 
this  virtue  treats  in  like  manner  known  and  unknown,  com- 
panions and  strangers.  Therefore  this  virtue  rather  than 
being  a  part  of  justice  is  opposed  thereto. 

On  the  contrary,  Macrobius  (De  Somno  Scip.  i.)  accounts 
friendship  a  part  of  justice. 

/  answer  that,  This  virtue  is  a  part  of  justice,  being 
annexed  to  it  as  to  a  principal  virtue.  Because  in  common 
with  justice  it  is  directed  to  another  person,  even  as  justice 
is:  yet  it  falls  short  of  the  notion  of  justice,  because  it  lacks 
the  full  aspect  of  debt,  whereby  one  man  is  bound  to 
another,  either  by  legal  debt,  which  the  law  binds  him  to 
pay,  or  by  some  debt  arising  out  of  a  favour  received. 
For  it  regards  merely  a  certain  debt  of  equity,  namely,  that 
we  behave  pleasantly  to  those  among  whom  we  dwell,  unless 
at  times,  for  some  reason,  it  be  necessary  to  displease  them 
for  some  good  purpose. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  we  have  said  above  (Q.  CIX.,  A.  3,  ad  1), 
because  man  is  a  social  animal  he  owes  his  fellow-man,  in 
equity,  the  manifestation  of  truth  without  which  human 
society  could  not  last.  Now  as  man  could  not  live  in  society 
without  truth,  so  likewise,  not  without  joy,  because,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  viii.),  no  one  could  abide  a  day  with 
the  sad  nor  with  the  joyless.  Therefore,  a  certain  natural 
equity  obliges  a  man  to  live  agreeably  with  his  fellow- men; 
unless  some  reason  should  oblige  him  to  sadden  them  for 
their  good. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  belongs  to  temperance  to  curb  pleasures 


Q.ii4.Art.2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  122 

of  the  senses.  But  this  virtue  regards  the  pleasures  of  fellow- 
ship, which  have  their  origin  in  the  reason,  in  so  far  as  one 
man  behaves  becomingly  towards  another.  Such  pleasures 
need  not  to  be  curbed  as  though  they  were  noisome. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  This  saying  of  the  Philosopher  does  not 
mean  that  one  ought  to  converse  and  behave  in  the  same 
way  with  acquaintances  and  strangers,  since,  as  he  says 
{ibid.),  it  is  not  fitting  to  please  or  displease  acquaintances 
and  strangers  in  the  same  way.  The  likeness  consists  in  this, 
that  we  ought  to  behave  towards  all  in  a  fitting  manner. 


QUESTION    CXV. 

OF  FLATTERY. 

(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  vices  opposed  to  the  aforesaid 
virtue:  (i)  Flattery,  and  (2)  Quarrelling.  Concerning  flat- 
tery there  are  two  points  of  inquiry:  (1)  Whether  flattery  is 
a  sin  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  a  mortal  sin  ? 


First  Article, 
whether  flattery  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  flattery  is  not  a  sin.  For 
flattery  consists  in  words  of  praise  offered  to  another  in  order 
to  please  him.  But  it  is  not  a  sin  to  praise  a  person,  accord- 
ing to  Prov.  xxxi.  28,  Her  children  rose  up  and  called  her 
blessed:  her  husband,  and  he  praised  her.  Moreover,  there  is 
no  evil  in  wishing  to  please  others,  according  to  1  Cor.  x.  33, 
I  ...  in  all  things  please  all  men.  Therefore  flattery  is  not 
a  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Evil  is  contrary  to  good,  and  blame  to 
praise.  But  it  is  not  a  sin  to  blame  evil.  Neither,  then,  is 
it  a  sin  to  praise  good,  which  seems  to  belong  to  flattery. 
Therefore  flattery  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Detraction  is  contrary  to  flattery. 
WTherefore  Gregory  says  (Moral,  xxii.  5)  that  detraction  is 
a  remedy  against  flattery.  It  must  be  observed,  says  he, 
that  by  the  wonderful  moderation  of  our  Ruler,  we  are  often 
allowed  to  be  rent  by  detractions  but  are  uplifted  by  immoderate 
praise,  so  that  whom  the  voice  of  the  flatterer  upraises,  the 

123 


Q.  115.  Art  i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  124 

tongue  of  the  detracter  may  humble.  But  detraction  is  an 
evil,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXIII.,  AA.  2,  3).  Therefore 
flattery  is  a  good. 

On  the  contrary,  A  gloss  on  Ezech.  xiii.  18,  Woe  to  them 
that  sew  cushions  under  every  elbow,  says,  that  is  to  say, 
sweet  flattery.     Therefore  flattery  is  a  sin. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXIV.,  A.  1,  ad  3), 
although  the  friendship  of  which  we  have  been  speaking,  or 
affability,  intends  chiefly  the  pleasure  of  those  among  whom 
one  lives,  yet  it  does  not  fear  to  displease  when  it  is  a  question 
of  obtaining  a  certain  good,  or  of  avoiding  a  certain  evil. 
Accordingly,  if  a  man  were  to  wish  always  to  speak  pleasantly 
to  others,  he  would  exceed  the  mode  of  pleasing,  and  would 
therefore  sin  by  excess.  If  he  do  this  with  the  mere  inten- 
tion of  pleasing  he  is  said  to  be  complaisant,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  6) :  whereas  if  he  do  it  with  the  intention 
of  making  some  gain  out  of  it,  he  is  called  a  flatterer  or 
adulator.  As  a  rule,  however,  the  term  flattery  is  wont  to 
be  applied  to  all  who  wish  to  exceed  the  mode  of  virtue 
in  pleasing  others  by  words  or  deeds  in  their  ordinary 
behaviour  towards  their  fellows. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  One  may  praise  a  person  both  well  and  ill, 
according  as  one  observes  or  omits  the  due  circumstances. 
For  if  while  observing  other  due  circumstances  one  were  to 
wish  to  please  a  person  by  praising  him,  in  order  thereby 
to  console  him,  or  that  he  may  strive  to  make  progress  in 
good,  this  will  belong  to  the  aforesaid  virtue  of  friendship. 
But  it  would  belong  to  flattery,  if  one  wished  to  praise  a 
person  for  things  in  which  he  ought  not  to  be  praised;  since 
perhaps  they  are  evil,  according  to  Ps.  ix.  24,  The  sinner  is 
praised  in  the  desires  of  his  soul ;  or  they  may  be  uncertain, 
according  to  Ecclus.  xxvii.  8,  Praise  not  a  man  before  he 
speaketh,  and  again  (ibid.  xi.  2),  Praise  not  a  man  for  his 
beauty;  or  because  there  may  be  fear  lest  human  praise 
should  incite  him  to  vainglory,  wherefore  it  is  written, 
(ibid.  xi.  30),  Praise  not  any  man  before  death.  Again,  in  like 
manner  it  is  right  to  wish  to  please  a  man  in  order  to  foster 
charity,  so  that  he  may  make  spiritual  progress  therein. 


125  FLATTERY  Q.  ii5.Art.2 

But  it  would  be  sinful  to  wish  to  please  men  for  the  sake  of 
vainglory  or  gain,  or  to  please  them  in  something  evil, 
according  to  Ps.  Hi.  6,  God  hath  scattered  the  bones  of  them  that 
please  men,  and  according  to  the  words  of  the  Apostle 
(Gal.  i.  10),  ///  yet  pleased  men,  I  should  not  be  the  servant  of 
Christ. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Even  to  blame  evil  is  sinful,  if  due  circum- 
stances be  not  observed;  and  so  too  is  it  to  praise  good. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Nothing  hinders  two  vices  being  contrary 
to  one  another.  Wherefore  even  as  detraction  is  evil,  so 
is  flattery,  which  is  contrary  thereto  as  regards  what  is  said, 
but  not  directly  as  regards  the  end.  Because  flattery  seeks 
to  please  the  person  flattered,  whereas  the  detractor  seeks 
not  the  displeasure  of  the  person  defamed,  since  at  times 
he  defames  him  in  secret,  but  seeks  rather  his  defamation. 

Second  Article, 
whether  flattery  is  a  mortal  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  flattery  is  a  mortal  sin.  For, 
according  to  Augustine  (Euchirid.  xii.),  a  thing  is  evil  because 
it  is  harmful.  But  flattery  is  most  harmful,  according  to 
Ps.  ix.  24,  For  the  sinner  is  praised  in  the  desires  of  his  soul, 
and  the  unjust  man  is  blessed.  The  sinner  hath  provoked  the 
Lord.  Wherefore  Jerome  says  (Ep.  ad  Celant.):  Nothing  so 
easily  corrupts  the  human  mind  as  flattery :  and  a  gloss  on 
Ps.  lxix.  4,  Let  them  be  presently  turned  away  blushing  for 
shame  that  say  to  me  :  'Tis  well,  'Tis  well,  says:  The  tongue  of 
the  flatterer  harms  more  than  the  sword  of  the  persecutor. 
Therefore  flattery  is  a  most  grievous  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Whoever  does  harm  by  words,  harms 
himself  no  less  than  others:  wherefore  it  is  written 
(Ps.  xxxvi.  15):  Let  their  sword  enter  into  their  own  heaHs. 
Now  he  that  flatters  another  induces  him  to  sin  mortally: 
hence  a  gloss  on  Ps.  cxl.  5,  Let  not  the  oil  of  the  sinner  fatten 
my  head,  says:  The  false  praise  of  the  flatterer  softens  the  mind 
by  depriving  it  of  the  rigidity  of  truth  and  renders  it  susceptive 


Q.ii5.Art.2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  126 

of  vice.  Much  more,  therefore,  does  the  flatterer  sin  in  him- 
self. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  is  written  in  the  Decretals  (D.  XLVI. , 
Cap.  3) :  The  cleric  who  shall  be  found  to  spend  his  time  in 
flattery  and  treachery  shall  be  degraded  from  his  office.  Now 
such  a  punishment  as  this  is  not  inflicted  save  for  mortal 
sin.     Therefore  flattery  is  a  mortal  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  in  a  sermon  on  Purgatory 
(xli.,  de  Sanctis)  reckons  among  slight  sins,  if  one  desire 
to  flatter  any  person  of  higher  standing,  whether  of  one's  own 
choice,  or  out  of  necessity. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXIL,  A.  2),  a  mortal 
sin  is  one  that  is  contrary  to  charity.  Now  flatteiy  is  some- 
times contrary  to  charity  and  sometimes  not.  It  is  contrary 
to  charity  in  three  ways.  First,  by  reason  of  the  very 
matter,  as  when  one  man  praises  another's  sin:  for 
this  is  contrary  to  the  love  of  God,  against  Whose  justice 
he  speaks,  and  contrary  to  the  love  of  his  neighbour,  whom 
he  encourages  to  sin.  Wherefore  this  is  a  mortal  sin, 
according  to  Isa.  v.  20,  Woe  to  you  that  call  evil  good. 
Secondly,  by  reason  of  the  intention,  as  when  one  man  flatters 
another,  so  that  by  deceiving  him  he  may  injure  him  in 
body  or  in  soul;  this  is  also  a  mortal  sin,  and  of  this  it  is 
written  (Prov.  xxvii.  6) :  Better  are  the  wounds  of  a  friend 
than  the  deceitful  kisses  of  an  enemy.  Thirdly,  by  way  of 
occasion,  as  when  the  praise  of  a  flatterer,  even  without  his 
intending  it,  becomes  to  another  an  occasion  of  sin.  In 
this  case  it  is  necessary  to  consider,  whether  the  occasion 
were  given  or  taken,  and  how  grievous  the  consequent 
downfall,  as  may  be  understood  from  what  has  been  said 
above  concerning  scandal  (Q.  XLIIL,  AA.  3,  4).  If,  how- 
ever, one  man  flatters  another  from  the  mere  craving  to 
please  others,  or  again  in  order  to  avoid  some  evil,  or  to 
acquire  something  in  a  case  of  necessity,  this  is  not  contrary 
to  charity.  Consequently  it  is  not  a  mortal  but  a  venial 
sin. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  passages  quoted  speak  of  the  flatterer 
who  praises  another's  sin.     Flattery  of  this  kind  is  said  to 


127  FLATTERY  Q.  h5.Art.2 

harm  more  than  the  sword  of  the  persecutor,  since  it  does 
harm  to  goods  that  are  of  greater  consequence,  namely, 
spiritual  goods.  Yet  it  does  not  harm  so  efficaciously,  since 
the  sword  of  the  persecutor  slays  effectively,  being  a  sufficient 
cause  of  death;  whereas  no  one  by  flattering  can  be  a 
sufficient  cause  of  another's  sinning,  as  was  shown  above 
(Q.  XLIII.,  A.  i,  ad  3:  I.-IL,  Q.  LXXIIL,  A.  8,  ad  3: 
Q.  LXXX.,  A.  1). 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  argument  applies  to  one  that  flatters 
with  the  intention  of  doing  harm:  for  such  a  man  harms 
himself  more  than  others,  since  he  harms  himself,  as  the 
sufficient  cause  of  sinning,  whereas  he  is  only  the  occasional 
cause  of  the  harm  he  does  to  others. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  passage  quoted  refers  to  the  man 
who  flatters  another  treacherously,  in  order  to  deceive  him. 


QUESTION    CXVI 

OF  QUARRELLING. 
(In  Two  Articles.) 


We  must  now  consider  quarrelling;  concerning  which  there 
are  two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  it  is  opposed  to  the 
virtue  of  friendship  ?  (2)  Of  its  comparison  with  flattery. 


First  Article. 

whether   quarrelling   is   opposed   to   the  virtue   of 
friendship  or   affability  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  quarrelling  is  not  opposed  to 
the  virtue  of  friendship  or  affability.  For  quarrelling  seems 
to  pertain  to  discord,  just  as  contention  does.  But  discord 
is  opposed  to  charity,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXVII. ,  A.  1). 
Therefore  quarrelling  is  also. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  It  is  written  (Prov.  xxvi.  21):  An  angry 
man  stirreih  up  strife.  Now  anger  is  opposed  to  meekness. 
Therefore  strife  or  quarrelling  is  also. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  is  written  (James  iv.  1) :  From 
whence  are  wars  and  quarrels  (Douay,  —  contentions) 
among  you?  Are  they  not  hence,  from  your  concupiscences 
which  war  in  your  members  ?  Now  it  would  seem  contrary 
to  temperance  to  follow  one's  concupiscences.  Therefore 
it  seems  that  quarrelling  is  opposed  not  to  friendship  but 
to  temperance. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  opposes  quarrelling  to 
friendship  {Ethic,  iv.  6). 

J  answer  that,   Quarrelling  consists  properly  in  words, 

128 


I2Q  QUARRELLING  Q.h6.Art.i 

when,  namely,  one  person  contradicts  another's  words. 
Now  two  things  may  be  observed  in  this  contradiction.  For 
sometimes  contradiction  arises  on  account  of  the  person 
who  speaks,  the  contradictor  refusing  to  consent  with  him 
from  lack  of  that  love  which  unites  minds  together,  and  this 
seems  to  pertain  to  discord,  which  is  contrary  to  charity. 
Whereas  at  times  contradiction  arises  by  reason  of  the  speaker 
being  a  person  to  whom  someone  does  not  fear  to  be  disagree- 
able :  whence  arises  quarrelling,  which  is  opposed  to  the  afore- 
said friendship  or  affability,  to  which  it  belongs  to  behave 
agreeably  towards  those  among  whom  we  dwell.  Hence 
the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  6)  that  those  who  are  opposed 
to  everything  with  the  intent  of  being  disagreeable,  and  care 
for  nobody,  are  said  to  be  peevish  and  quarrelsome. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Contention  pertains  rather  to  the  contra- 
diction of  discord,  while  quarrelling  belongs  to  the  con- 
tradiction which  has  the  intention  of  displeasing. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  direct  opposition  of  virtues  to  vices 
depends,  not  on  their  causes,  since  one  vice  may  arise  from 
many  causes,  but  on  the  species  of  their  acts.  And  although 
quarrelling  arises  at  times  from  anger,  it  may  arise  from 
many  other  causes,  hence  it  does  not  follow  that  it  is  directly 
opposed  to  meekness. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  James  speaks  there  of  concupiscence 
considered  as  a  general  evil  whence  all  vices  arise.  Thus, 
a  gloss  on  Rom.  vii.  7  says :  The  law  is  good,  since  by  for- 
bidding concupiscence,  it  forbids  all  evil. 

Second  Article. 

whether  quarrelling  is  a  more  grievous  sin  than 

flattery  ?■ 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  I.  It  seems  that  quarrelling  is  a  less  grievous 
sin  than  the  contrary  vice,  viz.  adulation  or  flattery.  For 
the  more  harm  a  sin  does  the  more  grievous  it  seems  to 
be.  Now  flattery  does  more  harm  than  quarrelling,  for 
it  is  written  (Isa.  iii.  12) :  0  My  people,  they  that  call  thee 

II.  ii/4  9 


Q.  ii6.Art.2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  130 

blessed,  the  same  deceive  thee,  and  destroy  the  way  of  thy  steps. 
Therefore  flattery  is  a  more  grievous  sin  than  quarrelling. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  There  appears  to  be  a  certain  amount 
of  deceit  in  flattery,  since  the  flatterer  says  one  thing,  and 
thinks  another:  whereas  the  quarrelsome  man  is  without 
deceit,  for  he  contradicts  openly,  Now  he  that  sins 
deceitfully  is  a  viler  man,  according  to  the  Philosopher 
(Ethic,  vii.  6).  Therefore  flattery  is  a  more  grievous  sin 
than  quarrelling. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Shame  is  fear  of  what  is  vile,  according 
to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  9).  But  a  man  is  more  ashamed 
to  be  a  flatterer  than  a  quarreller.  Therefore  quarrelling  is 
a  less  grievous  sin  than  flattery. 

On  the  contrary,  The  more  a  sin  is  inconsistent  with  the 
spiritual  state,  the  more  it  appears  to  be  grievous.  Now 
quarrelling  seems  to  be  more  inconsistent  with  the  spiritual 
state :  for  it  is  written  (1  Tim.  iii.  2,  3)  that  it  behoveth  a  bishop 
to  be  .  .  .  not  quarrelsome ;  and  (2  Tim.  ii.  24) :  The  servant 
of  the  Lord  must  not  wrangle.  Therefore  quarrelling  seems 
to  be  a  more  grievous  sin  than  flattery. 

I  answer  that,  We  can  speak  of  each  of  these  sins  in  two  ways. 
In  one  way  we  may  consider  the  species  of  either  sin,  and 
thus  the  more  a  vice  is  at  variance  with  the  opposite  virtue 
the  more  grievous  it  is.  Now  the  virtue  of  friendship  has 
a  greater  tendency  to  please  than  to  displease:  and  so  the 
quarrelsome  man,  who  exceeds  in  giving  displeasure,  sins 
more  grievously  than  the  adulator  or  flatterer,  who  exceeds 
in  giving  pleasure.  In  another  way  we  may  consider  them 
as  regards  certain  external  motives,  and  thus  flattery  is 
sometimes  more  grievous,  for  instance  when  one  intends 
by  deception  to  acquire  undue  honour  or  gain;  while  some- 
times quarrelling  is  more  grievous,  for  instance,  when  one 
intends  either  to  deny  the  truth,  or  to  hold  up  the  speaker 
to  contempt. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Just  as  the  flatterer  may  do  harm  by 
deceiving  secretly,  so  the  quarreller  may  do  harm  sometimes 
by  assailing  openly.  Now,  other  things  being  equal,  it  is 
more  grievous  to  harm  a  person  openly,  by  violence  as  it 


131  QUARRELLING  Q.  h6.Art.2 

were,  than  secretly.  Wherefore  robbery  is  a  more  grievous 
sin  than  theft,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXVL,  A.  9). 

Reply  Obj.  2.  In  human  acts,  the  more  grievous  is  not 
always  the  more  vile.  For  the  comeliness  of  a  man  has  its 
source  in  his  reason:  wherefore  the  sins  of  the  flesh,  whereby 
the  flesh  enslaves  the  reason,  are  viler,  although  spiritual  sins 
are  more  grievous,  since  they  proceed  from  greater  contempt. 
In  like  manner,  sins  that  are  committed  through  deceit 
are  viler,  in  so  far  as  they  seem  to  arise  from  a  certain 
weakness,  and  from  a  certain  falseness  of  the  reason,  although 
sins  that  are  committed  openly  proceed  sometimes  from  a 
greater  contempt.  Hence  flattery,  through  being  accom- 
panied by  deceit,  seems  to  be  a  viler  sin;  while  quarrelling, 
through  proceeding  from  greater  contempt,  is  apparently 
more  grievous. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  in  the  objection,  shame  regards 
the  vileness  of  a  sin:  wherefore  a  man  is  not  always  more 
ashamed  of  a  more  grievous  sin,  but  of  a  viler  sin.  Hence 
it  is  that  a  man  is  more  ashamed  of  flattery  than  of  quarrel- 
ling, although  quarrelling  is  more  grievous. 


QUESTION  CXVII. 

OF  LIBERALITY. 
[In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  liberality  and  the  opposite  vices, 
namely,  covetousness  and  prodigality. 

Concerning  liberality  there  are  six  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  liberality  is  a  virtue  ?  (2)  What  is  its  matter  ? 
(3)  Of  its  act :  (4)  Whether  it  pertains  thereto  to  give  rather 
than  to  take  ?  (5)  Whether  liberality  is  a  part  of  justice  ? 
(6)  Of  its  comparison  with  other  virtues. 

First  Article, 
whether  liberality  is  a  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  liberality  is  not  a  virtue.  For 
no  virtue  is  contrary  to  a  natural  inclination.  Now  it  is  a 
natural  inclination  for  one  to  provide  for  oneself  more  than 
for  others :  and  yet  it  pertains  to  the  liberal  man  to  do  the 
contrary,  since,  according  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  iv.  1), 
it  is  the  mark  of  a  liberal  man  not  to  look  to  himself,  so  that  he 
leaves  for  himself  the  lesser  things.  Therefore  liberality  is  not 
a  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Man  sustains  life  by  means  of  riches, 
and  wealth  contributes  to  happiness  instrumentally,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  i.  8.  Since,  then,  every  virtue  is  directed  to 
happiness,  it  seems  that  the  liberal  man  is  not  virtuous, 
for  the  Philosopher  says  of  him  {Ethic,  iv.  1)  that  he  is  inclined 
neither  to  receive  nor  to  keep  money,  but  to  give  it  away. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  virtues  are  connected  with  one 
another.     But  liberality  does  not  seem  to  be  connected  with 

132 


133  LIBERALITY  Q.  117.  Art.  i 

the  other  virtues:  since  many  are  virtuous  who  cannot  be 
liberal,  for  they  have  nothing  to  give;  and  many  give  or 
spend  liberally  who  are  not  virtuous  otherwise.  Therefore 
liberality  is  not  a  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  Ambrose  says  {De  Offic.  i.)that  the  Gospel 
contains  many  instances  in  which  a  just  liberality  is  incul- 
cated. Now  in  the  Gospel  nothing  is  taught  that  does  not 
pertain  to  virtue.     Therefore  liberality  is  a  virtue. 

/  answer  that,  As  Augustine  says  {De  Lib.  Arb.  ii.  19),  it 
belongs  to  virtue  to  use  well  the  things  that  we  can  use  ill.  Now 
we  may  use  both  well  and  ill,  not  only  the  things  that  are 
within  us,  such  as  the  powers  and  the  passions  of  the  soul, 
but  also  those  that  are  without,  such  as  the  things  of  this 
world  that  are  granted  us  for  our  livelihood.  Wherefore 
since  it  belongs  to  liberality  to  use  these  things  well,  it 
follows  that  liberality  is  a  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  According  to  Augustine  (Serm.  lxiv.  de 
Temp.)  and  Basil  [Horn,  in  Luc.  xii.  18)  excess  of  riches  is 
granted  by  God  to  some,  in  order  that  they  may  obtain  the 
merit  of  a  good  stewardship.  But  it  suffices  for  one  man  to 
have  few  things.  Wherefore  the  liberal  man  commendably 
spends  more  on  others  than  on  himself.  Nevertheless  we 
are  bound  to  be  more  provident  for  ourselves  in  spiritual 
goods,  in  which  each  one  is  able  to  look  after  himself  in  the 
first  place.  And  yet  it  does  not  belong  to  the  liberal  man 
even  in  temporal  firings  to  attend  so  much  to  others  as  to 
lose  sight  of  himself  and  those  belonging  to  him.  Wherefore 
Ambrose  says  {De  Offic.  i.) ;  It  is  a  commendable  liberality  not 
to  neglect  your  relatives  if  you  know  them  to  be  in  want. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  does  not  belong  to  a  liberal  man  so  to 
give  away  his  riches  that  nothing  is  left  for  his  own  support, 
nor  the  wherewithal  to  perform  those  acts  of  virtue  whereby 
happiness  is  acquired.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv. 
r)  that  the  liberal  man  does  not  neglect  his  own,  wishing  thus 
to  be  of  help  to  certain  people;  and  Ambrose  says  {De  Offic.  i.) 
that  Our  Lord  does  not  wish  a  man  to  pour  out  his  riches  all 
at  once,  but  to  dispense  them  :  unless  he  do  as  Eliseus  did,  who 
slew  his  oxen  and  fed  the  poor,  that  he  might  not  be  bound  by 


Q.ii7.Art.i    THE  " SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  134 

any  household  cares.  For  this  belongs  to  the  state  of  perfec- 
tion, of  which  we  shall  speak  farther  on  (Q.  CLXXXIV., 
Q.  CLXXXVI.,  A.  3), 

It  must  be  observed,  however,  that  the  very  act  of  giving 
away  one's  possessions  liberally,  in  so  far  as  it  is  an  act  of 
virtue,  is  directed  to  happiness. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  1),  those 
who  spend  much  on  intemperance  are  not  liberal  but  prodigal  ; 
and  likewise  whoever  spends  what  he  has  for  the  sake  of  any 
other  sins.  Hence  Ambrose  says  (De  Offic.  i.) :  If  you  assist 
another  to  rob  others  of  their  possessions,  your  honesty  is  not 
to  be  commended,  nor  is  your  liberality  genuine  if  you  give 
for  the  sake  of  boasting  rather  than  of  pity.  Wherefore  those 
who  lack  other  virtues,  though  they  spend  much  on  certain 
evil  works,  are  not  liberal. 

Again,  nothing  hinders  certain  people  from  spending  much 
on  good  uses,  without  having  the  habit  of  liberality:  even 
as  men  perform  works  of  other  virtues,  before  having  the 
habit  of  virtue,  though  not  in  the  same  way  as  virtuous 
people,  as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXV.,  A.  1).  In  like 
manner  nothing  prevents  a  virtuous  man  from  being  liberal, 
although  he  be  poor.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  1) : 
Liberality  is  proportionate  to  a  mans  substance,  i.e.  his  means 
for  it  consists,  not  in  the  quantity  given,  but  in  the  habit  of  the 
giver :  and  Ambrose  says  {De  Offic.  i.)  that  it  is  the  heart  that 
makes  a  gift  rich  or  poor,  and  gives  things  their  value. 

Second  Article, 
whether  liberality  is  about  money  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  I.  It  seems  that  liberality  is  not  about  money. 
For  every  moral  virtue  is  about  operations  and  passions. 
Now  it  is  proper  to  justice  to  be  about  operations,  as  stated 
in  Ethic,  v.  1.  Therefore,  since  liberality  is  a  moral  virtue, 
it  seems  that  it  is  about  passions  and  not  about  money. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  It  belongs  to  a  liberal  man  to  make  use 
of  any  kind  of  wealth.     Now  natural  riches  are  more  real 


i35  LIBERALITY  Q.  117-  Art.  2 

than  artificial  riches,  according  to  the  Philosopher  {Polit.  i. 
5,  6).     Therefore  liberality  is  not  chiefly  about  money. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Different  virtues  have  different  matter, 
since  habits  are  distinguished  by  their  objects.  But  ex- 
ternal things  are  the  matter  of  distributive  and  commutative 
justice.     Therefore  they  are  not  the  matter  of  liberality. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  1)  that 
liberality  seems  to  be  a  mean  in  the  matter  of  money. 

I  answer  that,  According  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  iv. 
ibid.)  it  belongs  to  the  liberal  man  to  part  with  things. 
Hence  liberality  is  also  called  open-handedness  {largitas), 
because  that  which  is  open  does  not  withhold  things 
but  parts  with  them.  The  term  liberality  seems  also  to 
allude  to  this,  since  when  a  man  quits  hold  of  a  thing  he 
frees  {liberat)  it,  so  to  speak,  from  his  keeping  and  owner- 
ship, and  shows  his  mind  to  be  free  of  attachment  thereto. 
Now  those  things  which  are  the  subject  of  a  man's  free- 
handedness  towards  others  are  the  goods  he  possesses,  which 
are  denoted  by  the  term  money.  Therefore  the  proper 
matter  of  liberality  is  money. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  stated  above  (A.  1,  ad  3),  liberality 
depends  not  on  the  quantity  given,  but  on  the  heart  of  the 
giver.  Now  the  heart  of  the  giver  is  disposed  according  to 
the  passions  of  love  and  desire,  and  consequently  those  of 
pleasure  and  sorrow,  towards  the  things  given.  Hence  the 
interior  passions  are  the  immediate  matter  of  liberality,  while 
exterior  money  is  the  object  of  those  same  passions. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  Augustine  says  in  his  book  De  Discipline 
Christi  {Tract,  de  divers,  i.) ,  everything  whatsoever  man  has 
on  earth,  and  whatsoever  he  owns,  goes  by  the  name  of 
'pecunia'  {money),  because  in  olden  times  men's  possessions 
consisted  entirely  of  'pecora'  {flocks).  And  the  Philosopher 
says  {Ethic,  iv.  1) :  We  give  the  name  of  money  to  anything 
that  can  be  valued  in  currency. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Justice  establishes  equality  in  external 
things,  but  has  nothing  to  do,  properly  speaking,  with  the 
regulation  of  internal  passions :  wherefore  money  is  in  one 
way  the  matter  of  liberality,  and  in  another  way  of  justice. 


Q.ii7.Art.3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA "  136 

Third  Article, 
whether  using  money  is  the  act  of  liberality  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  using  money  is  not  the  act  of 
liberality.  For  different  virtues  have  different  acts.  But 
using  money  is  becoming  to  other  virtues,  such  as  justice 
and  magnificence.  Therefore  it  is  not  the  proper  act  of 
liberality. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  It  belongs  to  a  liberal  man,  not  only  to 
give  but  also  to  receive  and  keep.  But  receiving  and 
keeping  do  not  seem  to  be  connected  with  the  use  of  money. 
Therefore  using  money  seems  to  be  unsuitably  assigned  as 
the  proper  act  of  liberality. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  use  of  money  consists  not  only  in 
giving  it  but  also  in  spending  it.  But  the  spending  of  money 
refers  to  the  spender,  and  consequently  is  not  an  act  of 
liberality:  for  Seneca  says  (De  Bene/,  v.):  A  man  is  not 
liberal  by  giving  to  himself.  Therefore  not  every  use  of 
money  belongs  to  liberality. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  1) :  In 
whatever  matter  a  man  is  virtuous,  he  will  make  the  best  use 
of  that  matter:  Therefore  he  that  has  the  virtue  with  regard  to 
money  will  make  the  best  use  of  riches.  Now  such  is  the 
liberal  man.  Therefore  the  good  use  of  money  is  the  act  of 
liberality. 

/  answer  that,  The  species  of  an  act  is  taken  from  its  object, 
as  stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  XVIII.,  A.  2).  Now  the  object 
or  matter  of  liberality  is  money  and  whatever  has  a  money 
value,  as  stated  in  the  foregoing  Article  {ad  2).  And  since 
every  virtue  is  consistent  with  its  object,  it  follows  that, 
since  liberality  is  a  virtue,  its  act  is  consistent  with  money. 
Now  money  comes  under  the  head  of  useful  goods,  since  all 
external  goods  are  directed  to  man's  use.  Hence  the  proper 
act  of  liberality  is  making  use  of  money  or  riches. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  It  belongs  to  liberality  to  make  good  use  of 
riches  as  such,  because  riches  are  the  proper  matter  of 


137  LIBERALITY  Q.  1 1 7.  Art.  3 

liberality.  On  the  other  hand  it  belongs  to  justice  to  make 
use  of  riches  under  another  aspect,  namely,  that  of  debt, 
in  so  far  as  an  external  thing  is  due  to  another.  And  it 
belongs  to  magnificence  to  make  use  of  riches  under  a  special 
aspect,  in  so  far,  to  wit,  as  they  are  employed  for  the  fulfil- 
ment of  some  great  deed.  Hence  magnificence  stands  in 
relation  to  liberality  as  something  in  addition  thereto,  as 
we  shall  explain  farther  on  (Q.  CXXXIV.). 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  belongs  to  a  virtuous  man  not  only  to 
make  good  use  of  his  matter  or  instrument,  but  also  to 
provide  opportunities  for  that  good  use.  Thus  it  belongs 
to  a  soldier's  fortitude  not  only  to  wield  his  sword  against 
the  foe,  but  also  to  sharpen. his  sword  and  keep  it  in  its 
sheath.  Thus,  too,  it  belongs  to  liberality  not  only  to  use 
money,  but  also  to  keep  it  in  preparation  and  safety  in  order 
to  make  fitting  use  of  it. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  (A.  2,  ad  1),  the  internal  passions 
whereby  man  is  affected  towards  money  are  the  proximate 
matter  of  liberality.  Hence  it  belongs  to  liberality  before 
all  that  a  man  should  not  be  prevented  from  making  any 
due  use  of  money  through  an  inordinate  affection  for  it. 
Now  there  is  a  twofold  use  of  money :  one  consists  in  apply- 
ing it  to  one's  own  use,  and  would  seem  to  come  under  the 
designation  of  costs  or  expenditure ;  while  the  other  consists 
in  devoting  it  to  the  use  of  others,  and  comes  under  the 
head  of  gifts.  Hence  it  belongs  to  liberality  that  one  be 
not  hindered  by  an  immoderate  love  of  money,  either  from 
spending  it  becomingly,  or  from  making  suitable  gifts. 
Therefore  liberality  is  concerned  with  giving  and  spending, 
according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  1).  The  saying  of 
Seneca  refers  to  liberality  as  regards  giving :  for  a  man  is  not 
said  to  be  liberal  for  the  reason  that  he  gives  something  to 
himself. 


Q.  117.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  138 


Fourth  Article, 
whether  it  belongs  to  a  liberal  man  chiefly  to 

GIVE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  it  does  not  belong  to  a  liberal 
man  chiefly  to  give.  For  liberality,  like  all  other  moral 
virtues,  is  regulated  by  prudence.  Now  it  seems  to  belong 
very  much  to  prudence  that  a  man  should  keep  his  riches. 
Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  1)  that  those  who 
have  not  earned  money,  but  have  received  the  money  earned  by 
others,  spend  it  more  liberally,  because  they  have  not  experi- 
enced the  want  of  it.  Therefore  it  seems  that  giving  does  not 
chiefly  belong  to  the  liberal  man. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  No  man  is  sorry  for  what  he  intends 
chiefly  to  do,  nor  does  he  cease  from  doing  it.  But  a  liberal 
man  is  sometimes  sorry  for  what  he  has  given,  nor  does  he 
give  to  all,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iv.  (loc.  cit.).  Therefore  it  does 
not  belong  chiefly  to  a  liberal  man  to  give. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  In  order  to  accomplish  what  he  intends 
chiefly,  a  man  employs  all  the  ways  he  can.  Now  a  liberal 
man  is  not  a  beggar,  as  the  Philosopher  observes  (Ethic,  iv. 
loc.  cit.) ;  and  yet  by  begging  he  might  provide  himself  with 
the  means  of  giving  to  others.  Therefore  it  seems  that  he 
does  not  chiefly  aim  at  giving. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Man  is  bound  to  look  after  himself  rather 
than  others.  But  by  spending  he  looks  after  himself, 
whereas  by  giving  he  looks  after  others.  Therefore  it 
belongs  to  a  liberal  man  to  spend  rather  than  to  give. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  loc.  cit.) 
that  it  belongs  to  a  liberal  man  to  surpass  in  giving. 

I  answer  that,  It  is  proper  to  a  liberal  man  to  use  money. 
Now  the  use  of  money  consists  in  parting  with  it.  For  the 
acquisition  of  money  is  like  generation  rather  than  use: 
while  the  keeping  of  money,  in  so  far  as  it  is  directed  to 
facilitate  the  use  of  money,  is  like  a  habit.  Now  in  parting 
with  a  thing — for  instance,  when  we  throw  something — the 


139  LIBERALITY  Q.  1 1 7.  Art.  4 

farther  we  put  it  away  the  greater  the  force  (virtus)  employed. 
Hence  parting  with  money  by  giving  it  to  others  proceeds 
from  a  greater  virtue  than  when  we  spend  it  on  ourselves. 
But  it  is  proper  to  a  virtue  as  such  to  tend  to  what  is  more 
perfect,  since  virtue  is  a  kind  of  perfection  (Phys.  vii.  text.  17, 
18).     Therefore  a  liberal  man  is  praised  chiefly  for  giving. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  It  belongs  to  prudence  to  keep  money,  lest 
it  be  stolen  or  spent  uselessly.  But  to  spend  it  usefully  is 
not  less  but  more  prudent  than  to  keep  it  usefully:  since 
more  things  have  to  be  considered  in  money's  use,  which  is 
likened  to  movement,  than  in  its  keeping,  which  is  likened 
to  rest.  As  to  those  who,  having  received  money  that  others 
have  earned,  spend  it  more  liberally,  through  not  having 
experienced  the  want  of  it,  if  their  inexperience  is  the  sole 
cause  of  their  liberal  expenditure  they  have  not  the  virtue 
of  liberality.  Sometimes,  however,  this  inexperience  merely 
removes  the  impediment  to  liberality,  so  that  it  makes  them 
all  the  more  ready  to  act  liberally,  because,  not  unfre- 
quently,  the  fear  of  want  that  results  from  the  experience 
of  want  hinders  those  who  have  acquired  money  from  using 
it  up  by  acting  with  liberality;  as  does  likewise  the  love 
they  have  for  it  as  being  their  own  effect,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  1). 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  stated  in  this  and  the  preceding  Article, 
it  belongs  to  liberality  to  make  fitting  use  of  money,  and 
consequently  to  give  it  in  a  fitting  manner,  since  this  is  a 
use  of  money.  Again,  every  virtue  is  grieved  by  whatever  is 
contrary  to  its  act,  and  avoids  whatever  hinders  that  act. 
Now  two  things  are  opposed  to  suitable  giving;  namely,  not 
giving  what  ought  suitably  to  be  given,  and  giving  some- 
thing unsuitably.  Wherefore  the  liberal  man  is  grieved 
at  both :  but  especially  at  the  former,  since  it  is  more  opposed 
to  his  proper  act.  For  this  reason,  too,  he  does  not  give  to 
all :  since  his  act  would  be  hindered  were  he  to  give  to  every- 
one :  for  he  would  not  have  the  means  of  giving  to  those  to 
whom  it  were  fitting  for  him  to  give. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Giving  and  receiving  are  related  to  one 
another  as  action  and  passion.     Now  the  same  thing  is  not 


Q.ii7.Art.5    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  140 

the  principle  of  both  action  and  passion.  Hence,  since 
liberality  is  a  principle  of  giving,  it  does  not  belong  to  the 
liberal  man  to  be  ready  to  receive,  and  still  less  to  beg. 
Hence  the  verse  : 

In  this  world  he  that  wishes  to  be  pleasing  to  many 
Should  give  often,  take  seldom,  ask  never. 

But  he  makes  provision  in  order  to  give  certain  things 
according  as  liberality  requires;  such  are  the  fruits  of  his 
own  possessions,  for  he  is  careful  about  realizing  them  that 
he  may  make  a  liberal  use  thereof. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  To  spend  on  oneself  is  an  inclination  of 
nature;  hence  to  spend  money  on  others  belongs  properly 
to  a  virtue. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  liberality  is  a  part  of  justice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  liberality  is  not  a  part  of  justice. 
For  justice  regards  that  which  is  due.  Now  the  more  a  thing 
is  due  the  less  liberally  is  it  given.  Therefore  liberality  is 
not  a  part  of  justice,  but  is  incompatible  with  it. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Justice  is  about  operations,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  LVIII.,  A.  9:  I. -II.,  Q.  L.,  AA.  2,  3):  whereas 
liberality  is  chiefly  about  the  love  and  desire  of  money, 
which  are  passions.  Therefore  liberality  seems  to  belong 
to  temperance  rather  than  to  justice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  belongs  chiefly  to  liberality  to  give 
becomingly,  as  stated  (A.  4).  But  giving  becomingly 
belongs  to  beneficence  and  mercy,  which  pertain  to  charity, 
as  stated  above  (QQ.  XXX.,  XXXI.).  Therefore  liberality 
is  a  part  of  charity  rather  than  of  justice. 

On  the  contrary,  Ambrose  says  (De  Offic.  i.):  Justice  has 
to  do  with  the  fellowship  of  mankind.  For  the  notion  of  fellow- 
ship is  divided  into  two  parts,  justice  and  beneficence,  also 
called  liberality  or  kind-heartedness.  Therefore  liberality  per- 
tains to  justice. 

/  answer  that,  Liberality  is  not  a  species  of  justice,  since 


141  LIBERALITY  Q.  117.  Art.  5 

justice  pays  another  what  is  his,  whereas  liberality  gives 
another  what  is  one's  own.  There  are,  however,  two  points 
in  which  it  agrees  with  justice:  first,  that  it  is  directed 
chiefly  to  another,  as  justice  is;  secondly,  that  it  is  concerned 
with  external  things,  and  so  is  justice,  albeit  under  a  different 
aspect,  as  stated  in  this  Article  and  above  (A.  2,  ad  3). 
Hence  it  is  that  liberality  is  reckoned  by  some  to  be  a  part 
of  justice,  being  annexed  thereto  as  to  a  principal  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Although  liberality  does  not  consider  the 
legal  due  that  justice  considers,  it  considers  a  certain  moral 
due.  This  due  is  based  on  a  certain  fittingness  and  not  on 
an  obligation :  so  that  it  answers  to  the  idea  of  due  in  the 
lowest  degree. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Temperance  is  about  concupiscence  in 
pleasures  of  the  body.  But  the  concupiscence  and  delight 
in  money  is  not  referable  to  the  body  but  rather  to  the  soul. 
Hence  liberality  does  not  properly  pertain  to  temperance. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  giving  of  beneficence  and  mercy  pro- 
ceeds from  the  fact  that  a  man  has  a  certain  affection  towards 
the  person  to  whom  he  gives :  wherefore  this  giving  belongs 
to  charity  or  friendship.  But  the  giving  of  liberality  arises 
from  a  person  being  affected  in  a  certain  way  towards  money, 
in  that  he  desires  it  not  nor  loves  it :  so  that  when  it  is  fitting 
he  gives  it  not  only  to  his  friends  but  also  to  those  whom 
he  knows  not.  Hence  it  belongs  not  to  charity,  but  to 
justice,  which  is  about  external  things. 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  liberality  is  the  greatest  of  the 

VIRTUES  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  liberality  is  the  greatest  of  the 
virtues.  For  every  virtue  of  man  is  a  likeness  to  the  divine 
goodness.  Now  man  is  likened  chiefly  by  liberality  to 
God,  Who  giveth  to  all  men  abundantly,  and  upbraideth  not 
(James  i.  5).  Therefore  liberality  is  the  greatest  of  the 
virtues. 


Q.  n7.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  142 

Obj.  2.  Further,  According  to  Augustine  {De  Trin.  vi.  8), 
in  things  that  are  great,  but  not  in  bulk,  to  be  greatest  is  to  be 
best.  Now  the  nature  of  goodness  seems  to  pertain  mostly  to 
liberality,  since  the  good  is  self -communicative,  according 
to  Dionysius  {Div.  Norn.  iv.).  Hence  Ambrose  says  {De 
Offic.  i.)  that  justice  inclines  to  severity,  liberality  to  goodness. 
Therefore  liberality  is  the  greatest  of  virtues. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Men  are  honoured  and  loved  on  account 
of  virtue.  Now  Boethius  says  {De  Consol.  ii.)  that  bounty 
above  all  makes  a  man  famous  :  and  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic,  iv.  1)  that  among  the  virtuous  the  liberal  are  the  most 
beloved.     Therefore  liberality  is  the  greatest  of  virtues. 

On  the  contrary,  Ambrose  says  {De  Offic.  i.)  that  justice 
seems  to  be  more  excellent  than  liberality,  although  liberality 
is  more  pleasing.  The  Philosopher  also  says  {Rhet.  i.  9)  that 
brave  and  just  men  are  honoured  chiefly  and,  after  them,  those 
who  are  liberal. 

I  answer  that,  Every  virtue  tends  towards  a  good;  where- 
fore the  greater  virtue  is  that  which  tends  towards  the  greater 
good.  Now  liberality  tends  towards  a  good  in  two  ways: 
in  one  way,  primarily  and  of  its  own  nature;  in  another  way, 
consequently.  Primarily  and  of  its  very  nature  it  tends  to 
set  in  order  one's  own  affection  towards  the  possession  and 
use  of  money.  In  this  way  temperance,  which  moderates 
desires  and  pleasures  relating  to  one's  own  body,  takes  pre- 
cedence of  liberality :  and  so  do  fortitude  and  justice,  which, 
in  a  manner,  are  directed  to  the  common  good,  one  in  time 
of  peace,  the  other  in  time  of  war:  while  all  these  are  pre- 
ceded by  those  virtues  which  are  directed  to  the  Divine 
good.  For  the  Divine  good  surpasses  all  manner  of  human 
good;  and  among  human  goods  the  public  good  surpasses  the 
good  of  the  individual ;  and  of  the  last  named  the  good  of  the 
body  surpasses  those  goods  that  consist  of  external  things. 

Again,  liberality  is  ordained  to  a  good  consequently,  and 
in  this  way  it  is  directed  to  all  the  aforesaid  goods.  For  by 
reason  of  his  not  being  a  lover  of  money,  it  follows  that  a  man 
readily  makes  use  of  it,  whether  for  himself,  or  for  the  good 
of  others,  or  for  God's  glory.     Thus  it  derives  a  certain 


143  LIBERALITY  Q.h7.Art.6 

excellence  from  being  useful  in  many  ways.  Since,  however, 
we  should  judge  of  things  according  to  that  which  is  com- 
petent to  them  primarily  and  in  respect  of  their  nature, 
rather  than  according  to  that  which  pertains  to  them  con- 
sequently, it  remains  to  be  said  that  liberality  is  not  the 
greatest  of  virtues. 

Reply  Obj.  I.  God's  giving  proceeds  from  His  love  for 
those  to  whom  He  gives,  not  from  His  affection  towards  the 
things  He  gives,  wherefore  it  seems  to  pertain  to  charity,  the 
greatest  of  virtues,  rather  than  to  liberality. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Every  virtue  shares  the  nature  of  goodness 
by  giving  forth  its  own  act :  and  the  acts  of  certain  other 
virtues  are  better  than  money  which  liberality  gives  forth. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  friendship  whereby  a  liberal  man  is 
beloved  is  not  that  which  is  based  on  virtue,  as  though  he 
were  better  than  others,  but  that  which  is  based  on  utility, 
because  he  is  more  useful  in  external  goods,  which  as  a  rule 
men  desire  above  all  others  For  the  same  reason  he  becomes 
famous. 


QUESTION  CXVIII. 

OF  THE  VICES  OPPOSED  TO  LIBERALITY,   AND   IN  THE 
FIRST  PLACE,  OF  COVETOUSNESS. 

(In  Eight  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  vices  opposed  to  liberality :  and 
(i)  covetousness :  (2)  prodigality. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry: 
(1)  Whether  covetousness  is  a  sin  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  a 
special  sin  ?  (3)  To  which  virtue  it  is  opposed  :  (4)  Whether 
it  is  a  mortal  sin  ?  (5)  Whether  it  is  the  most  grievous  of 
sins  ?  (6)  Whether  it  is  a  sin  of  the  flesh  or  a  spiritual  sin  ? 
(7)  Whether  it  is  a  capital  vice  ?  (8)  Of  its  daughters. 

First  Article, 
whether  covetousness  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  covetousness  is  not  a  sin.  For 
covetousness  (avaritia)  denotes  a  certain  greed  for  gold 
(arts  aviditas*),  because,  to  wit,  it  consists  in  a  desire  for 
money,  under  which  all  external  goods  may  be  comprised. 
Now  it  is  not  a  sin  to  desire  external  goods :  since  man  desires 
them  naturally,  both  because  they  are  naturally  subject  to 
man,  and  because  by  their  means  man's  life  is  sustained 
(for  which  reason  they  are  spoken  of  as  his  substance). 
Therefore  covetousness  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Every  sin  is  against  either  God,  or  one's 
neighbour,  or  oneself,  as  statedabove  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXXII.,  A.  4). 
But  covetousness  is  not,  properly  speaking,  a  sin  against 

*  The  Latin  for  covetousness  avaritia  is  derived  from  aveo  to 
desire;  but  the  Greek  (friXapyvpta  signifies  literally  love  of  money: 
and  it  is  to  this  that  S.  Thomas  is  alluding  (cf.  A.  2.  Obj.  2). 

144 


145  COVETOUSNESS  Q.hS.Art.  i 

God:  since  it  is  opposed  neither  to  religion  nor  to  the  theo- 
logical virtues,  by  which  man  is  directed  to  God.  Nor  again 
is  it  a  sin  against  oneself,  for  this  pertains  properly  to  glut- 
tony and  lust,  of  which  the  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  vi.  18) :  He 
that  commiUeth  fornication  sinneth  against  his  own  body.  In 
like  manner  neither  is  it  apparently  a  sin  against  one's  neigh- 
bour, since  a  man  harms  no  one  by  keeping  what  is  his  own. 
Therefore  covetousness  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Things  that  occur  naturally  are  not  sins. 
Now  covetousness  comes  naturally  to  old  age  and  every  kind 
of  defect,  according  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  iv.  1).  There- 
fore covetousness  is  not  a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Heb.  xiii.  5):  Let  your 
manners  be  without  covetousness,  contented  with  such  things 
as  you  have. 

I  answer  that,  In  whatever  things  good  consists  in  a  due 
measure,  evil  must  of  necessity  ensue  through  excess  or 
deficiency  of  that  measure.  Now  in  all  things  that  are  for 
an  end,  the  good  consists  in  a  certain  measure:  since  what- 
ever is  directed  to  an  end  must  needs  be  commensurate  with 
the  end,  as,  for  instance,  medicine  is  commensurate  with 
health,  as  the  Philosopher  observes  (Polit.  i.  6).  External 
goods  come  under  the  head  of  things  useful  for  an  end,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  CXVIL,  A.  3:  I.-IL,  Q.  II.,  A.  1).  Hence 
it  must  needs  be  that  man's  good  in  their  respect  consists  in 
a  certain  measure,  in  other  words,  that  man  seek,  according 
to  a  certain  measure,  to  have  external  riches,  in  so  far  as  they 
are  necessary  for  him  to  live  in  keeping  with  his  condition 
of  life.  Wherefore  it  will  be  a  sin  for  him  to  exceed  this 
measure,  by  wishing  to  acquire  or  keep  them  immoderately. 
This  is  what  is  meant  by  covetousness,  which  is  defined  as 
immoderate  love  of  possessing.  It  is  therefore  evident  that 
covetousness  is  a  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  It  is  natural  to  man  to  desire  external  things 
as  means  to  an  end:  wherefore  this  desire  is  devoid  of  sin, 
in  so  far  as  it  is  held  in  check  by  the  rule  taken  from  the 
nature  of  the  end.  But  covetousness  exceeds  this  rule,  and 
therefore  is  a  sin. 

11.  ii.  4.  10 


Q.  n8.  Art.  i    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  146 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Covetousness  may  signify  immoderation 
about  external  things  in  two  ways.  First,  so  as  to  regard 
immediately  the  acquisition  and  keeping  of  such  things, 
when,  to  wit,  a  man  acquires  or  keeps  them  more  than  is 
due.  In  this  way  it  is  a  >in  directly  against  one's  neighbour, 
since  one  man  cannot  over-abound  in  external  riches,  with- 
out another  man  lacking  them,  for  temporal  goods  cannot 
be  possessed  by  many  at  the  same  time.  Secondly,  it  may 
signify  immoderation  in  the  internal  affection  which  a  man 
has  for  riches,  when,  for  instance,  a  man  loves  them,  desires 
them,  or  delights  in  them,  immoderately.  In  this  way  by 
covetousness  a  man  sins  against  himself,  because  it  causes 
disorder  in  his  affections,  though  not  in  his  body  as  do  the 
sins  of  the  flesh. 

As  a  consequence,  however,  it  is  a  sin  against  God,  just 
as  all  mortal  sins,  inasmuch  as  man  contemns  things  eternal 
for  the  sake  of  temporal  things. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Natural  inclinations  should  be  regulated 
according  to  reason,  which  is  the  governing  power  in  human 
nature.  Hence  though  old  people  seek  more  greedily  the  aid 
of  external  things,  just  as  everyone  that  is  in  need  seeks  to 
have  his  need  supplied,  they  are  not  excused  from  sin  if  they 
exceed  this  due  measure  of  reason  with  regard  to  riches. 

Second  Article, 
whether  covetousness  is  a  special  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  covetousness  is  not  a  special 
sin.  For  Augustine  says  (De  Lib.  Arb.  iii.):  Covetousness, 
which  in  Greek  is  called  ^cXapyupla,  applies  not  only  to  silver  or 
money,  but  also  to  anything  that  is  desired  immoderately. 
Now  in  every  sin  there  is  immoderate  desire  of  something, 
because  sin  consists  in  turning  away  from  the  immutable 
good,  and  adhering  to  mutable  goods,  as  stated  above  (I. -II., 
Q.  LXXI.,  A.  VI.,  Obj.  3).  Therefore  covetousness  is  a 
general  sin. 

Obj.   2.  Further,   According   to   Isidore    (Etym.   x.),   the 


147  COVETOUSNESS  Q.  h8.Art.2 

covetous  (avarus)  man  is  so  called  because  he  is  greedy  for 
brass  {avidus  ceris),  i.e.  money :  wherefore  in  Greek  covetous 
ness  is  called  cfytXapyvpia,  i.e.  love  of  silver.  Now  silver, 
which  stands  for  money,  signifies  all  external  goods  the  value 
of  which  can  be  measured  by  money,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXVIL,  A.  2,  ad  2).  Therefore  covet ousness  is  a  desire 
for  any  external  thing:  and  consequently  seems  to  be  a 
general  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  A  gloss  on  Rom.  vii.  7,  For  I  had  not 
known  concupiscence,  says :  The  law  is  good,  since  by  forbidding 
concupiscence,  it  forbids  all  evil.  Now  the  law  seems  to  forbid 
especially  the  concupiscence  of  covetousness :  hence  it  is 
written  (Exod.  xx.  17) :  Thou  shall  not  covet  thy  neighbour's 
goods.  Therefore  the  concupiscence  of  covetousness  is  all 
evil,  and  so  covetousness  is  a  general  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Covetousness  is  numbered  together  with 
other  special  sins  (Rom.  i.  29),  where  it  is  written:   Being 
filled    with    all    iniquity,    malice,   fornication,    covetousness 
(Douay, — avarice) ,  etc. 

/  answer  that,  Sins  take  their  species  from  their  objects, 
as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXXIL,  A.  1).  Now  the  object 
of  a  sin  is  the  good  towards  which  an  inordinate  appetite 
tends.  Hence  where  there  is  a  special  aspect  of  good  in- 
ordinately desired,  there  is  a  special  kind  of  sin.  Now  the 
useful  good  differs  in  aspect  from  the  delightful  good.  And 
riches,  as  such,  come  under  the  head  of  useful  good,  since 
they  are  desired  under  the  aspect  of  being  useful  to  man. 
Consequently  covetousness  is  a  special  sin,  forasmuch  as 
it  is  an  immoderate  love  of  having  possessions,  which  are 
comprised  under  the  name  of  money,  whence  covetousness 
(avaritia)  is  denominated. 

Since,  however,  the  verb  to  have,  which  seems  to  have  been 
originally  employed  in  connection  with  possessions  whereof 
we  are  absolute  masters,  is  applied  to  many  other  things 
(thus  a  man  is  said  to  have  health,  a  wife,  clothes,  and  so 
forth,  as  stated  in  De  Prcedicamentis) ,  consequently  the  term 
covetousness  has  been  amplified  to  denote  all  immoderate 
desire  for  having  anything  whatever.     Thus  Gregory  says 


Q.  118.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  148 

in  a  homily  (xvi.  in  Ev.)  that  covetousness  is  a  desire  not  only 
for  money,  but  also  for  knowledge  and  high  places,  when 
prominence  is  immoderately  sought  after.  In  this  way  covetous- 
ness is  not  a  special  sin :  and  in  this  sense  Augustine  speaks 
of  covetousness  in  the  passage  quoted  in  the  First  Objec- 
tion. Wherefore  this  suffices  for  the  Reply  to  the  First 
Objection. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  All  those  external  things  that  are  subject  to 
the  uses  of  human  life  are  comprised  under  the  term  money, 
inasmuch  as  they  have  the  aspect  of  useful  good.  But  there 
are  certain  external  goods  that  can  be  obtained  by  money, 
such  as  pleasures,  honours,  and  so  forth,  which  are  desirable 
under  another  aspect.  Wherefore  the  desire  for  such  things 
is  not  properly  called  covetousness,  in  so  far  as  it  is  a  special 
vice. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  This  gloss  speaks  of  the  inordinate  concu- 
piscence for  anything  whatever.  For  it  is  easy  to  understand 
that  if  it  is  forbidden  to  covet  another's  possessions,  it  is 
also  forbidden  to  covet  those  things  that  can  be  obtained 
by  means  of  those  possessions. 

Third  Article, 
whether  covetousness  is  opposed  to  liberality  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  covetousness  is  not  opposed 
to  liberality.  For  Chrysostom,  commenting  on  Matth.  v.  6, 
Blessed  are  they  that  hunger  and  thirst  after  justice,  says 
{Horn.  xv.  in  Matth.)  that  there  are  two  kinds  of  justice,  one 
general,  and  the  other  special,  to  which  covetousness  is 
opposed:  and  the  Philosopher  says  the  same  (Ethic,  v.  2). 
Therefore  covetousness  is  not  opposed  to  liberality. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  sin  of  covetousness  consists  in  a  man's 
exceeding  the  measure  in  the  things  he  possesses.  But  this 
measure  is  appointed  by  justice.  Therefore  covetousness 
is  directly  opposed  to  justice  and  not  to  liberality. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Liberality  is  a  virtue  that  observes  the 
mean  between  two  contrary  vices,  as  the  Philosopher  states 


149  COVETOUSNESS  Q.  118.ART.3 

{Ethic,  i.  7;  iv.  1).  But  covetousness  has  no  contrary  and 
opposite  sin,  according  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  v.  1,  2). 
Therefore  covetousness  is  not  opposed  to  liberality. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Eccles.  v.  9) :  A  covetous  man 
shall  not  be  satisfied  with  money,  and  he  that  loveth  riches  shall 
have  no  fruits  from  them.  Now  not  to  be  satisfied  with  money 
and  to  love  it  inordinately  are  opposed  to  liberality,  which 
observes  the  mean  in  the  desire  of  riches.  Therefore  covetous- 
ness is  opposed  to  liberality. 

/  answer  that,  Covetousness  denotes  immoderation  with 
regard  to  riches  in  two  ways.  First,  immediately  in  respect 
of  the  acquisition  and  keeping  of  riches.  In  this  way  a  man 
obtains  money  beyond  his  due,  by  stealing  or  retaining 
another's  property.  This  is  opposed  to  justice,  and  in  this 
sense  covetousness  is  mentioned  (Ezech.  xxii.  27) :  Her 
princes  in  the  midst  of  her  are  like  wolves  ravening  the  prey 
to  shed  blood  .  .  .  and  to  run  after  gains  through  covetousness. 
Secondly,  it  denotes  immoderation  in  the  interior  affections 
for  riches;  for  instance,  when  a  man  loves  or  desires  riches 
too  much,  or  takes  too  much  pleasure  in  them,  even  if  he  be 
unwilling  to  steal.  In  this  way  covetousness  is  opposed  to 
liberality,  which  moderates  these  affections,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXVTL,  A.  2,  ad  3,  A.  3,  ad  3,  A.  6).  In  this  sense  covet- 
ousness is  spoken  of  (2  Cor.  ix.  5) :  That  they  would  .  .  . 
prepare  this  blessing  before  promised,  to  be  ready,  so  as  a 
blessing,  not  as  covetousness,  where  a  gloss  observes  :  Lest 
they  should  regret  what  they  had  given,  and  give  but  little. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Chrysostom  and  the  Philosopher  are  speak- 
ing of  covetousness  in  the  first  sense :  covetousness  in  the 
second  sense  is  called  illiberality*  by  the  Philosopher. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  belongs  properly  to  justice  to  appoint 
the  measure  in  the  acquisition  and  keeping  of  riches  from 
the  point  of  view  of  legal  due,  so  that  a  man  should  neither 
take  nor  retain  another's  property.  But  liberality  appoints 
the  measure  of  reason,  principally  in  the  interior  affections, 
and  consequently  in  the  exterior  taking  and  keeping  of 
money,  and  in  the  spending  of  the  same,  in  so  far  as  these 

*  avektv&epia. 


Q.  1 18.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  150 

proceed  from  the  interior  affection,  looking  at  the  matter 
from  the  point  of  view  not  of  the  legal  but  of  the  moral  debt, 
which  latter  depends  on  the  rule  of  reason. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Covetousness  as  opposed  to  justice  has  no 
opposite  vice :  since  it  consists  in  having  more  than  one 
ought  according  to  justice,  the  contrary  of  which  is  to  have 
less  than  one  ought,  and  this  is  not  a  sin  but  a  punishment. 
But  covetousness  as  opposed  to  liberality  has  the  vice  of 
prodigality  opposed  to  it. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  covetousness  is  always  a  mortal  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  covetousness  is  always  a  mortal 
sin.  For  no  one  is  worthy  of  death  save  for  a  mortal  sin. 
But  men  are  worthy  of  death  on  account  of  covetousness. 
For  the  Apostle  after  saying  (Rom.  i.  29) :  Being  filled  with 
all  iniquity  .  .  .  fornication,  covetousness  (Douay, — avarice), 
etc.,  adds  [verse  32) :  They  who  do  such  things  are  worthy  oj 
death.     Therefore  covetousness  is  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  least  degree  of  covetousness  is  to 
hold  to  one's  own  inordinately.  But  this  seemingly  is  a 
mortal  sin:  for  Basil  says  (Serm.  super.  Luc.  xii.  18):  It  is 
the  hungry  man's  bread  that  thou  keepest  back,  the  naked 
man's  cloak  that  thou  hoardest,  the  needy  man's  money 
that  thou  possessest,  hence  thou  despoilest  as  many  as  thou 
mightest  succour. 

Now  it  is  a  mortal  sin  to  do  an  injustice  to  another,  since 
it  is  contrary  to  the  love  of  our  neighbour.  Much  more 
therefore  is  all  covetousness  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  No  one  is  struck  with  spiritual  blindness 
save  through  a  mortal  sin,  for  this  deprives  a  man  of  the 
light  of  grace.  But,  according  to  Chrysostom,*  Lust  for 
money  brings  darkness  on  the  soul.  Therefore  covetousness, 
which  is  lust  for  money,  is  a  mortal  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  A  gloss  on  1  Cor.  iii.  12,  If  any  man  build 

*  Horn.  xv.  in  the  Opus  Imperfectum,  falsely  ascribed  to  S.  John 
Chrysostom. 


151  CO VETOUSNESS  Q.  1 1 8.  Art.  4 

upon  this  foundation,  says  (cf.  S.  Augustine,  De  Fide  et 
Opev.  xvi.)  that  he  builds  wood,  hay,  stubble,  who  thinks  in 
the  things  of  the  world,  how  he  may  please  the  world,  which 
pertains  to  the  sin  of  covetousness.  Now  he  that  builds 
wood,  hay,  stubble,  sins  not  mortally  but  venially,  for  it 
is  said  of  him  that  he  shall  be  saved,  yet  so  as  by  fire.  There- 
fore covetousness  is  sometimes  a  venial  sin. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  3)  covetousness  is  two- 
fold. In  one  way  it  is  opposed  to  justice,  and  thus  it  is  a 
mortal  sin  in  respect  of  its  genus.  For  in  this  sense  covetous- 
ness consists  in  the  unjust  taking  or  retaining  of  another's 
property,  and  this  belongs  to  theft  or  robbery,  which  are 
mortal  sins,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXVL,  AA.  6,  8).  Yet 
venial  sin  may  occur  in  this  kind  of  covetousness  by  reason 
of  imperfection  of  the  act,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXVL,  A.  6, 
ad  3),  when  we  were  treating  of  theft. 

In  another  way  covetousness  may  be  taken  as  opposed 
to  liberality:  in  which  sense  it  denotes  inordinate  love  of 
riches.  Accordingly,  if  the  love  of  riches  becomes  so  great 
as  to  be  preferred  to  charity,  in  such  wise  that  a  man, 
through  love  of  riches,  fear  not  to  act  counter  to  the  love  of 
God  and  his  neighbour,  covetousness  will  then  be  a  mortal 
sin.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  the  inordinate  nature  of  his  love 
stops  short  of  this,  so  that  although  he  love  riches  too  much, 
yet  he  does  not  prefer  the  love  of  them  to  the  love  of  God, 
and  is  unwilling  for  the  sake  of  riches  to  do  anything  in 
opposition  to  God  or  his  neighbour,  then  covetousness  is  a 
venial  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Covetousness  is  numbered  together  with 
mortal  sins,  by  reason  of  the  aspect  under  which  it  is  a 
mortal  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Basil  is  speaking  of  a  case  wherein  a  man  is 
bound  by  a  legal  debt  to  give  of  his  goods  to  the  poor,  either 
through  fear  of  their  want  or  on  account  of  his  having  too 
much. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Lust  for  riches,  properly  speaking,  brings 
darkness  on  the  soul,  when  it  puts  out  the  light  of  charity, 
by  preferring  the  love  of  riches  to  the  love  of  God. 


Q.  i is.  Art.  5   THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  152 


Fifth  Article, 
whether  covetousness  is  the  greatest  of  sins  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  covetousness  is  the  greatest  of 
sins.  For  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  x.  9) :  Nothing  is  more  wicked 
than  a  covetous  man,  and  the  text  continues :  There  is  not  a 
more  wicked  thing  than  to  love  money:  for  such  a  one  setteih 
even  his  own  soul  to  sale.  Tully  also  says  (De  Offic.  i.,  under 
the  heading — True  magnanimity  is  based  chiefly  on  two 
things)  :  Nothing  is  so  narrow  or  little  minded  as  to  love  money. 
But  this  pertains  to  covetousness.  Therefore  covetousness 
is  the  most  grievous  of  sins. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  more  a  sin  is  opposed  to  charity,  the 
more  grievous  it  is.  Now  covetousness  is  most  opposed  :o 
charity:  for  Augustine  says  (QQ.  LXXXIII.  qu.  36)  that 
greed  is  the  bane  of  charity.  Therefore  covetousness  is  the 
greatest  of  sins. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  gravity  of  a  sin  is  indicated  by  its 
being  incurable:  wherefore  the  sin  against  the  Holy  Ghost 
is  said  to  be  most  grievous,  because  it  is  irremissible.  But 
covetousness  in  an  incurable  sin :  hence  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic,  iv.  1)  that  old  age  and  helplessness  of  any  kind  makemen 
illiberal.    Therefore  covetousness  is  the  most  grievous  of  sins. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  The  Apostle  says  (Eph.  v.  5)  that  covetous- 
ness is  a  serving  of  idols.  Now  idolatry  is  reckoned  among 
the  most  grievous  sins.     Therefore  covetousness  is  also. 

On  the  contrary,  Adultery  is  a  more  grievous  sin  than  theft, 
according  to  Prov.  vi.  30.  But  theft  pertains  to  covetous- 
ness.   Therefore  covetousness  is  not  the  most  grievous  of  sins. 

I  answer  that,  Every  sin,  from  the  very  fact  that  it  is  an 
evil,  consists  in  the  corruption  or  privation  of  some  good: 
while,  in  so  far  as  it  is  voluntary,  it  consists  in  the  desire 
of  some  good.  Consequently  the  order  of  sins  may  be  con- 
sidered in  two  ways.  First,  on  the  part  of  the  good  that  is 
despised  or  corrupted  by  sin,  and  then  the  greater  the  good 
the  graver  the  sin.     From  this  point  of  view  a  sin  that  is 


153  COVETOUSNESS  Q.ii8.Art.5 

against  God  is  most  grievous;  after  this  comes  a  sin  that  is 
committed  against  a  man's  person,  and  after  this  comes  a 
sin  against  external  things,  which  are  deputed  to  man's  use, 
and  this  seems  to  belong  to  covetousness.  Secondly,  the 
degrees  of  sin  may  be  considered  on  the  part  of  the  good 
to  which  the  human  appetite  is  inordinately  subjected;  and 
then  the  lesser  the  good,  the  more  deformed  is  the  sin :  for  it 
is  more  shameful  to  be  subject  to  a  lower  than  to  a  higher 
good.  Now  the  good  of  external  things  is  the  lowest  of 
human  goods :  since  it  is  less  than  the  good  of  the  body,  and 
this  is  less  than  the  good  of  the  soul,  which  is  less  than  the< 
Divine  good.  From  this  point  of  view  the  sin  of  covetous- 
ness, whereby  the  human  appetite  is  subjected  even  to 
external  things,  has  in  a  way  a  greater  deformity.  Since, 
however,  corruption  or  privation  of  good  is  the  formal 
element  in  sin,  while  conversion  to  a  mutable  good  is  the 
material  element,  the  gravity  of  the  sin  is  to  be  judged  from 
the  point  of  view  of  the  good  corrupted,  rather  than  from 
that  of  the  good  to  which  the  appetite  is  subjected.  Hence 
we  must  assert  that  covetousness  is  not  simply  the  most 
grievous  of  sins. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  These  authorities  speak  of  covetousness 
on  the  part  of  the  good  to  which  the  appetite  is  subjected. 
Hence  (Ecclus.  x.  10)  it  is  given  as  a  reason  that  the  covetous 
man  setteth  his  own  soul  to  sale  ;  because,  to  wit,  he  exposes 
his  soul — that  is,  his  life — to  danger  for  the  sake  of  money. 
Hence  the  text  continues :  Because  while  he  liveth  he  hath  cast 
away — that  is,  despised — his  bowels,  in  order  to  make  money. 
Tully  also  adds  that  it  is  the  mark  of  a  narrow  mind,  namely, 
that  one  be  willing  to  be  subject  to  money. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Augustine  is  taking  greed  generally,  in 
reference  to  any  temporal  good,  not  in  its  special  accepta- 
tion for  covetousness :  because  greed  for  any  temporal  good 
is  the  bane  of  charity,  inasmuch  as  a  man  turns  away  from 
the  Divine  good  through  cleaving  to  a  temporal  good. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  sin  against  the  Holy  Ghost  is  incurable 
in  one  way,  covetousness  in  another.  For  the  sin  against 
the  Holy  Ghost  is  incurable  by  reason  of  contempt:  for 


Q.  118.  Art.  5    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  154 

instance,  because  a  man  contemns  God's  mercy,  or  His 
justice,  or  some  one  of  those  things  whereby  man's  sins  are 
healed:  wherefore  incurability  of  this  kind  points  to  the 
greater  gravity  of  the  sin.  On  the  other  hand,  covetousness 
is  incurable  on  the  part  of  a  human  defect;  a  thing  which 
human  nature  ever  seeks  to  remedy,  since  the  more  deficient 
one  is  the  more  one  seeks  relief  from  external  things,  and 
consequently  the  more  one  gives  way  to  covetousness. 
Hence  incurability  of  this  kind  is  an  indication  not  of  the 
sin  being  more  grievous,  but  of  its  being  somewhat  more 
dangerous. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Covetousness  is  compared  to  idolatry  on 
account  of  a  certain  likeness  that  it  bears  to  it :  because  the 
covetous  man,  like  the  idolater,  subjects  himself  to  an  ex- 
ternal creature,  though  not  in  the  same  way.  For  the  idolater 
subjects  himself  to  an  external  creature  by  paying  it  Divine 
honour,  whereas  the  covetous  man  subjects  himself  to  an 
external  creature  by  desiring  it  immoderately  for  use,  not 
for  worship.  Hence  it  does  not  follow  that  covetousness 
is  as  grievous  a  sin  as  idolatry. 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  covetousness  is  a  spiritual  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  covetousness  is  not  a  spiritual 
sin.  For  spiritual  sins  seem  to  regard  spiritual  goods.  But 
the  matter  of  covetousness  is  bodily  goods,  namely,  external 
riches.     Therefore  covetousness  is  not  a  spiritual  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Spiritual  sin  is  condivided  with  sin  of  the 
flesh.  Now  covetousness  is  seemingly  a  sin  of  the  flesh,  for 
it  results  from  the  corruption  of  the  flesh,  as  instanced  in 
old  people  who,  through  corruption  of  carnal  nature,  fall 
into  covetousness.  Therefore  covetousness  is  not  a  spiritual 
sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  A  sin  of  the  flesh  is  one  by  which  man's 
body  is  disordered,  according  to  the  saying  of  the  Apostle 
(1  Cor.  vi.  18),  He  that  committeth  fornication  sinneth  against 


155  COVETOUSNESS  Q.  n8.  Art.6 

his  own  body.  Now  covetousness  disturbs  man  even  in  his 
body;  wherefore  Chrysostom  {Horn.  xxix.  in  Matth.)  com- 
pares the  covetous  man  to  the  man  who  was  possessed  by 
the  devil  (Mark  v.)  and  was  troubled  in  body.  Therefore 
covetousness  seems  not  to  be  a  spiritual  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  {Moral,  xxxi.)  numbers  covetous- 
ness among  spiritual  vices. 

I  answer  that,  Sins  are  seated  chiefly  in  the  affections :  and 
all  the  affections  or  passions  of  the  soul  have  their  term 
in  pleasure  and  sorrow,  according  to  the  Philosopher 
{Ethic,  ii.  5).  Now  some  pleasures  are  carnal  and  some 
spiritual.  Carnal  pleasures  are  those  which  are  consum- 
mated in  the  carnal  senses — for  instance,  the  pleasures  of  the 
table  and  sexual  pleasures:  while  spiritual  pleasures  are 
those  which  are  consummated  in  the  mere  apprehension  of 
the  soul.  Accordingly,  sins  of  the  flesh  are  those  which  are 
consummated  in  carnal  pleasures,  while  spiritual  sins  are 
consummated  in  pleasures  of  the  spirit  without  pleasure  of 
the  flesh.  Such  is  covetousness:  for  the  covetous  man 
takes  pleasure  in  the  consideration  of  himself  as  a  possessor 
of  riches.     Therefore  covetousness  is  a  spiritual  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  I.  Covetousness  with  regard  to  a  bodily  object 
seeks  the  pleasure,  not  of  the  body  but  only  of  the  soul, 
forasmuch  as  a  man  takes  pleasure  in  the  fact  that  he 
possesses  riches :  wherefore  it  is  not  a  sin  of  the  flesh.  Never- 
theless by  reason  of  its  object  it  is  a  mean  between  purely 
spiritual  sins,  which  seek  spiritual  pleasure  in  respect  of 
spiritual  objects  (thus  pride  is  about  excellence),  and  purely 
carnal  sins,  which  seek  a  purely  bodily  pleasure  in  respect 
of  a  bodily  object. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Movement  takes  its  species  from  the  term 
whereto  and  not  from  the  term  wherefrom.  Hence  a  vice  of 
the  flesh  is  so  called  from  its  tending  to  a  pleasure  of  the 
flesh,  and  not  from  its  originating  in  some  defect  of  the 
flesh. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Chrysostom  compares  a  covetous  man  to 
the  man  who  was  possessed  by  the  devil,  not  that  the  former 
is  troubled  in  the  flesh  in  the  same  way  as  the  latter,  but  by 


Q.  118.  Art.  7    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  156 

way  of  contrast,  since  while  the  possessed  man,  of  whom 
we  read  in  Mark  v.,  stripped  himself,  the  covetous  man 
loads  himself  with  an  excess  of  riches. 


Seventh  Article, 
whether  covetousness  is  a  capital  vice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  covetousness  is  not  a  capital 
vice.  For  covetousness  is  opposed  to  liberality  as  the  mean, 
and  to  prodigality  as  extreme.  But  neither  is  liberality  a 
principal  virtue,  nor  prodigality  a  capital  vice.  Therefore 
covetousness  also  should  not  be  reckoned  a  capital  vice. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  As  stated  above  (I.-II.,  Q.  LXXXIV., 
AA.  3,  4),  those  vices  are  called  capital  which  have  principal 
ends,  to  which  the  ends  of  other  vices  are  directed.  But 
this  does  not  apply  to  covetousness:  since  riches  have  the 
aspect,  not  of  an  end,  but  rather  of  something  directed  to 
an  end,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  i.  5.  Therefore  covetousness  is 
not  a  capital  vice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Gregory  says  {Moral,  xv.)  that  covetous- 
ness arises  sometimes  from  pride,  sometimes  from  fear.  For 
there  are  those  who,  when  they  think  that  they  lack  the  needful 
for  their  expenses,  allow  the  mind  to  give  way  to  covetousness. 
And  there  are  others  who,  wishing  to  be  thought  more  of,  are 
incited  to  greed  for  other  people's  property.  Therefore  covetous- 
ness arises  from  other  vices  instead  of  being  a  capital  vice 
in  respect  of  other  vices. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  [Moral,  xxxi.)  reckons  covetous- 
ness among  the  capital  vices. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  in  the  Second  Objection,  a  capital 
vice  is  one  which  under  the  aspect  of  end  gives  rise  to  other 
vices:  because  when  an  end  is  very  desirable,  the  result  is 
that  through  desire  thereof  man  sets  about  doing  many 
things  either  good  or  evil.  Now  the  most  desirable  end  is 
happiness  or  felicity,  which  is  the  last  end  of  human  life, 
as  stated  above  (I.-II.,  Q.  I.,  AA.  4,  7,  8) :  wherefore  the  more 
a  thing  is  furnished  with  the  conditions  of  happiness,  the 


157  COVETOUSNESS  Q.  118.  Art.  7 

more  desirable  it  is.  Also  one  of  the  conditions  of  happiness 
is  that  it  be  self-sufficing,  else  it  would  not  set  man's 
appetite  at  rest,  as  the  last  end  does.  Now  riches  give  great 
promise  of  self-sufficiency,  as  Boethius  says  (De  Consol.  iii.) : 
the  reason  of  which,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  v.  5), 
is  that  we  use  money  in  token  of  taking  possession  of  some- 
thing, and  again  it  is  written  (Eccles.  x.  19) :  All  things  obey 
money.  Therefore  covetousness,  which  is  desire  for  money, 
is  a  capital  vice. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Virtue  is  perfected  in  accordance  with 
reason,  but  vice  is  perfected  in  accordance  with  the  inclina- 
tion of  the  sensitive  appetite.  Now  reason  and  sensitive 
appetite  do  not  belong  chiefly,  to  the  same  genus,  and  conse- 
quently it  does  not  follow  that  principal  vice  is  opposed  to 
principal  virtue.  Wherefore,  although  liberality  is  not  a 
principal  virtue,  since  it  does  not  regard  the  principal  good 
of  the  reason,  yet  covetousness  is  a  principal  vice,  because 
it  regards  money,  which  occupies  a  principal  place  among 
sensible  goods,  for  the  reason  given  in  the  Article. 

On  the  other  hand,  prodigality  is  not  directed  to  an  end 
that  is  desirable  principally,  indeed  it  seems  rather  to  result 
from  a  lack  of  reason.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic. 
iv.  1)  that  a  prodigal  man  is  a  fool  rather  than  a  knave. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  is  true  that  money  is  directed  to  some- 
thing else  as  its  end :  yet  in  so  far  as  it  is  useful  for  obtaining 
all  sensible  things,  it  contains,  in  a  way,  all  things  virtually. 
Hence  it  has  a  certain  likeness  to  happiness,  as  stated  in  the 
Article. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Nothing  prevents  a  capital  vice  from  arising 
sometimes  out  of  other  vices,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXVI., 
A.  4,  ad  1:  I.-IL,  Q.  LXXXIV.,  A.  4),  provided  that  itself 
be  frequently  the  source  of  others. 


Q.  1 1 8.  Art.  8    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  158 


Eighth  Article. 

whether  treachery,  fraud,  falsehood,  perjury,  rest- 
lessness, violence,  and  insensibility  to  mercy  are 
daughters  of  covetousness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  daughters  of  covetousness 
are  not  as  commonly  stated,  namely,  treachery,  fraud,  false- 
hood, perjury,  restlessness,  violence,  and  insensibility  to  mercy. 
For  covetousness  is  opposed  to  liberality,  as  stated  above 
(A.  3).  Now  treachery,  fraud,  and  falsehood  are  opposed 
to  prudence,  perjury  to  religion,  restlessness  to  hope,  or  to 
charity  which  rests  in  the  beloved  object,  violence  to  justice, 
insensibility  to  mercy.  Therefore  these  vices  have  no  con- 
nection with  covetousness. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Treachery,  fraud  and  falsehood  seem  to 
pertain  to  the  same  thing,  namely,  the  deceiving  of  one's 
neighbour.  Therefore  they  should  not  be  reckoned  as 
different  daughters  of  covetousness. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Isidore  (Comment,  in  Deut.)  enumerates 
nine  daughters  of  covetousness;  which  are  lying,  fraud, 
theft,  perjury,  greed  of  filthy  lucre,  false  witnessing,  violence, 
inhumanity,  rapacity.  Therefore  the  former  reckoning  of 
daughters  is  insufficient. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  The  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  1)  mentions 
many  kinds  of  vices  as  belonging  to  covetousness  which  he 
calls  illiberality,  for  he  speaks  of  those  who  are  sparing, 
tight-fisted,  skinflints*  miser  s,-\  who  do  illiberal  deeds,  and  of 
those  who  batten  on  whoredom,  usurers,  gamblers,  despoilers 
of  the  dead,  and  robbers.  Therefore  it  seems  that  the  afore- 
said enumeration  is  insufficient. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  Tyrants  use  much  violence  against  their 
subjects.  But  the  Philosopher  says  (ibid.)  that  tyrants  who 
destroy  cities  and  despoil  sacred  places  are  not  to  be  called 
illiberal,  i.e.  covetous.  Therefore  violence  should  not  be 
reckoned  a  daughter  of  covetousness. 

*     KV/JUVOirpLaTTJS.  \      Kt/J.filK€S. 


i5g  COVETOUSNESS  Q.  h8.Art.8 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  {Moral,  xxxi.)  assigns  to  covetous- 
ness  the  daughters  mentioned  above. 

/  answer  that,  The  daughters  of  covetousness  are  the  vices 
which  arise  therefrom,  especially  in  respect  of  the  desire  of 
an  end.  Now  since  covetousness  is  excessive  love  of  possess- 
ing riches,  it  exceeds  in  two  things.  For  in  the  first  place 
it  exceeds  in  retaining,  and  in  this  respect  covetousness  gives 
rise  to  insensibility  to  mercy,  because,  to  wit,  a  man's  heart 
is  not  softened  by  mercy  to  assist  the  needy  with  his  riches.* 
In  the  second  place  it  belongs  to  covetousness  to  exceed  in 
receiving,  and  in  this  respect  covetousness  may  be  considered 
in  two  ways.  First  as  in  the  thought  (affectu).  In  this  way 
it  gives  rise  to  restlessness,  by  hindering  man  with  excessive 
anxiety  and  care,  for  a  covetous  man  shall  not  be  satisfied  with 
money  (Eccles.  v.  9).  Secondly,  it  may  be  considered  in 
the  execution  (effectu).  In  this  way  the  covetous  man,  in 
acquiring  other  people's  goods,  sometimes  employs  force, 
which  pertains  to  violence,  sometimes  deceit,  and  then  if  he 
has  recourse  to  words,  it  is  falsehood,  if  it  be  mere  words, 
perjury  if  he  confirm  his  statement  by  oath;  if  he  has  recourse 
to  deeds,  and  the  deceit  affects  things,  we  have  fraud ;  if 
persons,  then  we  have  treachery,  as  in  the  case  of  Judas,  who 
betrayed  Christ  through  covetousness. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  There  is  no  need  for  the  daughters  of  a 
capital  sin  to  belong  to  that  same  kind  of  vice:  because  a 
sin  of  one  kind  allows  of  sins  even  of  a  different  kind  being 
directed  to  its  end;  seeing  that  it  is  one  thing  for  a  sin  to 
have  daughters,  and  another  for  it  to  have  species. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  These  three  are  distinguished  as  stated  in 
the  Article. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  These  nine  are  reducible  to  the  seven  afore- 
said. For  lying  and  false  witnessing  are  comprised  under 
falsehood,  since  false  witnessing  is  a  special  kind  of  lie,  just 
as  theft  is  a  special  kind  of  fraud,  wherefore  it  is  comprised 
under  fraud ;  and  greed  of  filthy  lucre  belongs  to  restlessness ; 
rapacity  is  comprised  under  violence,  since  it  is  a  species 
thereof;  and  inhumanity  is  the  same  as  insensibility  to 
mercy. 

*  See  Q.  XXX.  A.  1. 


Q.  iiS.Art.s    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  160 

Reply  Obj.  4.  The  vices  mentioned  by  Aristotle  are  species 
rather  than  daughters  of  illiberality  or  covetousness.  For 
a  man  may  be  said  to  be  illiberal  or  covetous  through  a 
defect  in  giving.  If  he  gives  but  little  he  is  said  to  be  sparing ; 
if  nothing,  he  is  tight-fisted :  if  he  gives  with  great  reluctance, 
he  is  said  to  be  a  k.v^lvoitp'kt'tt)^  {skinflint),  a  cummin-seller, 
as  it  were,  because  he  makes  a  great  fuss  about  things 
of  little  value.  Sometimes  a  man  is  said  to  be  illiberal  or 
covetous,  through  an  excess  in  receiving,  and  this  in  two 
wa}rs.  In  one  way,  through  making  money  by  disgraceful 
means,  whether  in  performing  shameful  and  servile  works 
by  means  of  illiberal  practices,  or  by  acquiring  more  through 
sinful  deeds,  such  as  whoredom  or  the  like,  or  by  making 
a  profit  where  one  ought  to  have  given  gratis,  as  in  the  case 
of  usury,  or  by  labouring  much  to  make  little  profit.  In 
another  way,  in  making  money  by  unjust  means,  whether 
by  using  violence  on  the  living,  as  robbers  do,  or  by 
despoiling  the  dead,  or  by  preying  on  one's  friends,  as 
gamblers  do. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  Just  as  liberality  is  about  moderate  sums 
of  money,  so  is  illiberality.  Wherefore  tyrants  who  take 
great  things  by  violence,  are  said  to  be,  not  illiberal,  but 
unjust. 


QUESTION    CXIX. 

OF  PRODIGALITY. 

(In  Three  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  prodigality,  under  which  head  there 
are  three  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  prodigality  is 
opposite  to  covetousness  ?  (2)  Whether  prodigality  is  a  sin  ? 
(3)  Whether  it  is  a  graver  sin  than  covetousness  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  prodigality  is  opposite  to  covetousness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  prodigality  is  not  opposite  to 
covetousness.  For  opposites  cannot  be  together  in  the  same 
subject.  But  some  are  at  the  same  time  prodigal  and 
covetous.  Therefore  prodigality  is  not  opposite  to  covetous- 
ness. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Opposites  relate  to  one  same  thing.  But 
covetousness,  as  opposed  to  liberality,  relates  to  certain 
passions  whereby  man  is  affected  towards  money:  whereas 
prodigality  does  not  seem  to  relate  to  any  passions  of  the 
soul,  since  it  is  not  affected  towards  money,  or  to  anything 
else  of  the  kind.  Therefore  prodigality  is  not  opposite  to 
covetousness. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Sin  takes  its  species  chiefly  from  its  end, 
as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXII.,  A.  3).  Now  prodigality 
seems  always  to  be  directed  to  some  unlawful  end,  for  the 
sake  of  which  the  prodigal  squanders  his  goods.  Especially 
is  it  directed  to  pleasures,  wherefore  it  is  stated  (Luke  xv.  13) 
of  the  prodigal  son  that  he  wasted  his  substance  living  riot- 
ously. Therefore  it  seems  that  prodigality  is  opposed  to 
temperance  and  insensibility  rather  than  to  covetousness 
and  liberality. 

11.  ii.  4.  161  11 


Q.  119.  Art  t     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  162 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  ii.  7 :  iv.  1) 
that  prodigality  is  opposed  to  liberality,  and  illiberality,  to 
which  we  give  here  the  name  of  covetousness. 

/  answer  that,  In  morals  vices  are  opposed  to  one  another 
and  to  virtue  in  respect  of  excess  and  deficiency.  Now 
covetousness  and  prodigality  differ  variously  in  respect  of 
excess  and  deficiency.  Thus,  as  regards  affection  for  riches, 
the  covetous  man  exceeds  by  loving  them  more  than  he 
ought,  while  the  prodigal  is  deficient,  by  being  less  careful 
of  them  than  he  ought :  and  as  regards  external  action, 
prodigality  implies  excess  in  giving,  but  deficiency  in  re- 
taining and  acquiring,  while  covetousness,  on  the  contrary, 
denotes  deficiency  in  giving,  but  excess  in  acquiring  and 
retaining.  Hence  it  is  evident  that  prodigality  is  opposed 
to  covetousness. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Nothing  prevents  opposites  from  being  in 
the  same  subject  in  different  respects.  For  a  thing  is  de- 
nominated more  from  what  is  in  it  principally.  Now  just 
as  in  liberality,  which  observes  the  mean,  the  principal  thing 
is  giving,  to  which  receiving  and  retaining  are  subordinate, 
so,  too,  covetousness  and  prodigality  regard  principally  giving. 
Wherefore  he  who  exceeds  in  giving  is  said  to  be  prodigal, 
while  he  who  is  deficient  in  giving  is  said  to  be  covetous. 
Now  it  happens  sometimes  that  a  man  is  deficient  in  giving, 
without  exceeding  in  receiving,  as  the  Philosopher  observes 
(Ethic,  iv.  1) ,  And  in  like  manner  it  happens  sometimes  that 
a  man  exceeds  in  giving,  and  therefore  is  prodigal,  and  yet 
at  the  same  time  exceeds  in  receiving.  This  may  be  due 
either  to  some  kind  of  necessity,  since  while  exceeding  in 
giving  he  is  lacking  in  goods  of  his  own,  so  that  he  is  driven 
to  acquire  unduly,  and  this  pertains  to  covetousness;  or  it 
may  be  due  to  inordinateness  of  the  mind,  for  he  gives  not 
for  a  good  purpose,  but,  as  though  despising  virtue,  cares 
not  whence  or  how  he  receives  Wherefore  he  is  prodigal 
and  covetous  in  different  respects. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Prodigality  regards  passions  in  respect  of 
money,  not  as  exceeding,  but  as  deficient  in  them. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  prodigal  does  not  always  exceed  in 


163  PRODIGALITY  Q.  1 19.  Art.  2 

giving  for  the  sake  of  pleasures  which  are  the  matter  of 
temperance,  but  sometimes  through  being  so  disposed  as 
not  to  care  about  riches,  and  sometimes  on  account  of 
something  else.  More  frequently,  however,  he  inclines  to 
intemperance,  both  because  through  spending  too  much 
on  other  things  he  becomes  fearless  of  spending  on  objects 
of  pleasure,  to  which  the  concupiscence  of  the  flesh  is  more 
prone;  and  because  through  taking  no  pleasure  in  virtuous 
goods,  he  seeks  for  himself  pleasures  of  the  body.  Hence 
the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  1)  that  many  a  -prodigal  ends 
in  becoming  intemperate. 

Second  Article, 
whether  prodigality  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  prodigality  is  not  a  sin.  For 
the  Apostle  says  (1  Tim.  vi.  10):  Covetousness  (Douay, — 
Desire  of  money)  is  the  root  of  all  evils.  But  it  is  not  the  root 
of  prodigality,  since  this  is  opposed  to  it.  Therefore  prodi- 
gality is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  Apostle  says  (1  Tim.  vi.  17,  18): 
Charge  the  rich  of  this  world  .  .  .  to  give  easily,  to  communicate 
to  others.  Now  this  is  especially  what  prodigal  persons  do. 
Therefore  prodigality  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  belongs  to  prodigality  to  exceed  in 
giving  and  to  be  deficient  in  solicitude  about  riches.  But 
this  is  most  becoming  to  the  perfect,  who  fulfil  the  words  of 
our  Lord  (Matth.  vi.  34),  Be  not .  .  .  solicitous  for  to-morrow, 
and  (Matth.  xix.  21),  Sell  all  (Vulg., — what)  thou  hast,  and 
give  to  the  poor.     Therefore  prodigality  is  not  a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  The  prodigal  son  is  held  to  blame  for  his 
prodigality. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  1),  the  opposition 
between  prodigality  and  covetousness  is  one  of  excess  and 
deficiency;  either  of  which  destroys  the  mean  of  virtue. 
Now  a  thing  is  vicious  and  sinful  through  corrupting  the 
good  of  virtue.     Hence  it  follows  that  prodigality  is  a  sin, 


Q.  1 19.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  164 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Some  expound  this  saying  of  the  Apostle 
as  referring,  not  to  actual  covetousness,  but  to  a  kind  of 
habitual  covetousness,  which  is  the  concupiscence  of  the 
fomes*  whence  all  sins  arise.  Others  say  that  he  is  speaking 
of  a  general  covetousness  with  regard  to  any  kind  of  good : 
and  in  this  sense  also  it  is  evident  that  prodigality  arises 
from  covetousness;  since  the  prodigal  seeks  to  acquire  some 
temporal  good  inordinately,  namely,  to  give  pleasure  to 
others,  or  at  least  to  satisfy  his  own  will  in  giving.  But 
to  one  that  reviews  the  passage  correctly,  it  is  evident  that 
the  Apostle  is  speaking  literally  of  the  desire  of  riches,  for 
he  had  said  previously  (verse  9) :  They  that  will  become  rich, 
etc.  In  this  sense  covetousness  is  said  to  be  the  root  of  all 
evils,  not  that  all  evils  always  arise  from  covetousness,  but 
because  there  is  no  evil  that  does  not  at  some  time  arise  from 
covetousness.  Wherefore  prodigality  sometimes  is  born  of 
covetousness,  as  when  a  man  is  prodigal  in  going  to  great 
expense  in  order  to  curry  favour  with  certain  persons  from 
whom  he  may  receive  riches. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  Apostle  bids  the  rich  to  be  ready  to  give 
and  communicate  their  riches,  according  as  they  ought. 
The  prodigal  does  not  do  this:  since,  as  the  Philosopher 
remarks  (Ethic,  iv.  i),  his  giving  is  neither  good,  nor  for  a  good 
end,  nor  according  as  it  ought  to  be.  For  sometimes  they  give 
much  to  those  who  ought  to  be  poor,  namely,  to  buffoons  and 
flatterers,  whereas  to  the  good  they  give  nothing. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  excess  in  prodigality  consists  chiefly, 
not  in  the  total  amount  given,  but  in  the  amount  over  and 
above  what  ought  to  be  given.  Hence  sometimes  the  liberal 
man  gives  more  than  the  prodigal  man,  if  it  be  necessary. 
Accordingly  we  must  reply  that  those  who  give  all  their 
possessions  with  the  intention  of  following  Christ,  and  banish 
from  their  minds  all  solicitude  for  temporal  things,  are  not 
prodigal  but  perfectly  liberal. 

*  Cf.  I.-IL,  Q.  LXXXI.  A.  3.  ad  2. 


165  PRODIGALITY  Q.  1 19.  Art.  3 

Third  Article. 

whether  prodigality  is  a  more  grievous  sin  than 

covetousness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  prodigality  is  a  more  grievous 
sin  than  covetousness.  For  by  covetousness  a  man  injures 
his  neighbour  by  not  communicating  his  goods  to  him, 
whereas  by  prodigality  a  man  injures  himself,  because  the 
Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  1)  that  the  corruption  of  riches, 
which  are  the  means  whereby  a  man  lives,  is  an  undoing  of  his 
very  being.  Now  he  that  injures  himself  sins  more  grievously, 
according  to  Ecclus.  xiv.  5,  He  that  is  evil  to  himself,  to  whom 
will  he  be  good?  Therefore  prodigality  is  a  more  grievous 
sin  than  covetousness. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  A  disorder  that  is  accompanied  by  a 
laudable  circumstance  is  less  sinful.  Now  the  disorder  of 
covetousness  is  sometimes  accompanied  by  a  laudable  cir- 
cumstance, as  in  the  case  of  those  who  are  unwilling  to  spend 
their  own,  lest  they  be  driven  to  accept  from  others :  whereas 
the  disorder  of  prodigality  is  accompanied  by  a  circumstance 
that  calls  for  blame,  inasmuch  as  we  ascribe  prodigality 
to  those  who  are  intemperate,  as  the  Philosopher  observes 
{Ethic,  iv.  1).  Therefore  prodigality  is  a  more  grievous  sin 
than  covetousness. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Prudence  is  chief  among  the  moral  virtues, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  LVL,  A.  1,  ad  1 :  I.-IL,  Q.  LXL,  A.  2, 
ad  1).  Now  prodigality  is  more  opposed  to  prudence  than 
covetousness  is :  for  it  is  written  (Prov.  xxi.  20) :  There  is 
a  treasure  to  be  desired,  and  oil  in  the  dwelling  of  the  just;  and 
the  foolish  man  shall  spend  it :  and  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic,  iv.  6)  that  it  is  the  mark  of  a  fool  to  give  too  much  and 
receive  nothing.  Therefore  prodigality  is  a  more  grievous 
sin  than  covetousness. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  ibid.)  that 
the  prodigal  seems  to  be  much  better  than  the  illiberal  man. 

I  answer  thai,  Prodigality  considered  in  itself  is  a  less 


Q.  119.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  166 

grievous  sin  than  covetousness,  and  this  for  three  reasons. 
First,  because  covetousness  differs  more  from  the  opposite 
virtue :  since  giving,  wherein  the  prodigal  exceeds,  belongs 
to  liberality  more  than  receiving  or  retaining,  wherein  the 
covetous  man  exceeds.  Secondly,  because  the  prodigal  man 
is  of  use  to  the  many  to  whom  he  gives,  while  the  covetous 
man  is  of  use  to  no  one,  not  even  to  himself,  as  stated  in 
Ethic,  iv.  (loc.  cit.).  Thirdly,  because  prodigality  is  easily 
cured.  For  not  only  is  the  prodigal  on  the  way  to  old  age, 
which  is  opposed  to  prodigality,  but  he  is  easily  reduced  to 
a  state  of  want,  since  much  useless  spending  impoverishes 
him  and  makes  him  unable  to  exceed  in  giving.  Moreover, 
prodigality  is  easily  turned  into  virtue  on  account  of  its 
likeness  thereto.  On  the  other  hand,  the  covetous  man  is 
not  easily  cured,  for  the  reason  given  above  (Q.  CXVIII.,  A.  5, 
ad  3). 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  difference  between  the  prodigal  and 
the  covetous  man  is  not  that  the  former  sins  against  himself 
and  the  latter  against  another.  For  the  prodigal  sins 
against  himself  by  spending  that  which  is  his,  and  his  means 
of  support,  and  against  others  by  spending  the  wherewithal 
to  help  others.  This  applies  chiefly  to  the  clergy,  who  are  the 
dispensers  of  the  Church's  goods,  that  belong  to  the  poor 
whom  they  defraud  by  their  prodigal  expenditure.  In  like 
manner  the  covetous  man  sins  against  others,  by  being 
deficient  in  giving;  and  he  sins  against  himself,  through 
deficiency  in  spending :  wherefore  it  is  written  (Eccles.  vi.  2) : 
A  man  to  whom  God  hath  given  riches  .  .  .  yet  doth  not  give 
him  the  power  to  eat  thereof.  Nevertheless  the  prodigal  man 
exceeds  in  this,  that  he  injures  both  himself  and  others  yet 
so  as  to  profit  some;  whereas  the  covetous  man  profits 
neither  others  nor  himself,  since  he  does  not  even  use  his 
own  goods  for  his  own  profit. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  In  speaking  of  vices  in  general,  we  judge  of 
them  according  to  their  respective  natures :  thus,  with  regard 
to  prodigality  we  note  that  it  consumes  riches  to  excess,  and 
with  regard  to  covetousness  that  it  retains  them  to  excess. 
That  one  spend   too  much  for  the  sake  of    intemperance 


167  PRODIGALITY  Q.  1 19.  Art.  3 

points  already  to  several  additional  sins,  wherefore  the 
prodigal  of  this  kind  is  worse,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iv.  1.  That 
an  illiberal  or  covetous  man  refrain  from  taking  what  belongs 
to  others,  although  this  appears  in  itself  to  call  for  praise, 
yet  on  account  of  the  motive  for  which  he  does  so  it  calls 
for  blame,  since  he  is  unwilling  to  accept  from  others  lest 
he  be  forced  to  give  to  others. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  All  vices  are  opposed  to  prudence,  even  as 
all  virtues  are  directed  by  prudence :  wherefore  if  a  vice  be 
opposed  to  prudence  alone,  for  this  very  reason  it  is  deemed 
less  grievous. 


QUESTION  CXX. 

OF  "EPIKEIA"  OR  EQUITY. 
(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  epikeia,  under  which  head  there  are 
two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  epikeia  is  a  virtue? 
(2)  Whether  it  is  a  part  of  justice  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  "epikeia"*  is  a  virtue? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  epikeia  is  not  a  virtue.  For 
no  virtue  does  away  with  another  virtue.  Yet  epikeia  does 
away  with  another  virtue,  since  it  sets  aside  that  which  is 
just  according  to  law,  and  seemingly  is  opposed  to  severity. 
Therefore  epikeia  is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Augustine  says  (De  vera  Relig.  xxxi.) : 
With  regard  to  these  earthly  laws,  although  men  pass  judgement 
on  them  when  they  make  them,  yet,  when  once  they  are  made  and 
established,  the  judge  must  pronounce  judgement  not  on  them 
but  according  to  them.  But  seemingly  epikeia  pronounces 
judgement  on  the  law,  when  it  deems  that  the  law  should  not 
be  observed  in  some  particular  case.  Therefore  epikeia  is 
a  vice  rather  than  a  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Apparently  it  belongs  to  epikeia  to 
consider  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver,  as  the  Philosopher 
states  (Ethic,  v.  10).  But  it  belongs  to  the  sovereign  alone 
to  interpret  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver,  wherefore  the 
Emperor  says  in  the  Codex  of  Laws  and  Constitutions,  under 
Law  i. :  It  is  fitting  and  lawful  that  We  alone  should  interpret 


168 


169  EQUITY  Q.  120.  Art.  i 

between  equity  and  law.     Therefore  the  act   of   epikeia  is 
unlawful :  and  consequently  epikeia  is  not  a  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  {Ethic,  v.  10)  states  it  to 
be  a  virtue. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  XCVL,  A.  6), 
when  we  were  treating  of  laws,  since  human  actions,  with 
which  laws  are  concerned,  are  composed  of  contingent  sin- 
gulars and  are  innumerable  in  their  diversity,  it  was  not 
possible  to  lay  down  rules  of  law  that  would  apply  to  every 
single  case.  Legislators  in  framing  laws  attend  to  what 
commonly  happens :  although  if  the  law  be  applied  to  certain 
cases  it  will  frustrate  the  equality  of  justice  and  be  injurious 
to  the  common  good,  which  the  law  has  in  view.  Thus  the 
law  requires  deposits  to  be  restored,  because  in  the  majority 
of  cases  this  is  just.  Yet  it  happens  sometimes  to  be 
injurious — for  instance,  if  a  madman  were  to  put  his  sword  in 
deposit,  and  demand  its  delivery  while  in  a  state  of  madness, 
or  if  a  man  were  to  seek  the  return  of  his  deposit  in  order  to 
fight  against  his  country.  In  these  and  like  cases  it  is  bad 
to  follow  the  law,  and  it  is  good  to  set  aside  the  letter  of  the 
law  and  to  follow  the  dictates  of  justice  and  the  common 
good.  This  is  the  object  of  epikeia  which  we  call  equity. 
Therefore  it  is  evident  that  epikeia  is  a  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Epikeia  does  not  set  aside  that  which  is 
just  in  itself  but  that  which  is  just  as  by  law  established. 
Nor  is  it  opposed  to  severity,  which  follows  the  letter  of  the 
law  when  it  ought  to  be  followed.  To  follow  the  letter  of  the 
law  when  it  ought  not  to  be  followed  is  sinful.  Hence  it  is 
written  in  the  Codex  of  Laws  and  Constitutions  under  Law  v. : 
Without  doubt  he  transgresses  the  law  who  by  adhering  to  the 
letter  of  the  law  strives  to  defeat  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  would  be  passing  judgement  on  a  law  to 
say  that  it  was  not  well  made ;  but  to  say  that  the  letter  of 
the  law  is  not  to  be  observed  in  some  particular  case  is 
passing  judgement  not  on  the  law,  but  on  some  particular 
contingency. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Interpretation  is  admissible  in  doubtful 
cases  where  it  is  not  allowed  to  set  aside  the  letter  of  the  law 


Q.  120.  Art  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  170 

without  the  interpretation  of  the  sovereign.  But  when  the 
case  is  manifest  there  is  need,  not  of  interpretation,  but  of 
execution. 

Second  Article. 

whether  "  epikeia  "  is  a  part  of  justice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  epikeia  is  not  a  part  of  justice. 
For,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LVIII.,  A.  7),  justice  is  twofold, 
particular  and  legal.  Now  epikeia  is  not  a  part  of  par- 
ticular justice,  since  it  extends  to  all  virtues,  even  as  legal 
justice  does.  In  like  manner,  neither  is  it  a  part  of  legal 
justice,  since  its  operation  is  beside  that  which  is  established 
by  law.  Therefore  it  seems  that  epikeia  is  not  a  part  of 
justice. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  A  more  principal  virtue  is  not  assigned 
as  the  part  of  a  less  principal  virtue :  for  it  is  to  the  cardinal 
virtue,  as  being  principal,  that  secondary  virtues  are  as- 
signed as  parts.  Now  epikeia  seems  to  be  a  more  principal 
virtue  than  justice,  as  implied  by  its  name:  for  it  is  derived 
from  eiri,  i.e.  above,  and  hiiccuov,  i.e.  just.  Therefore  epikeia 
is  not  a  part  of  justice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  seems  that  epikeia  is  the  same  as 
modesty.  For  where  the  Apostle  says  (Phil.  iv.  5),  Let 
your  modesty  be  known  to  all  men  the  Greek  has  eVtet/ceta.* 
Now,  according  to  Tully  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.),  modesty  is  a  part 
of  temperance.     Therefore  epikeia  is  not  a  part  of  justice. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  v.  10)  that 
epikeia  is  a  kind  of  justice. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XLVIII.),  a  virtue  has 
three  kinds  of  parts,  subjective,  integral,  and  potential. 
A  subjective  part  is  one  of  which  the  whole  is  predicated 
essentially,  and  it  is  less  than  the  whole.  This  may  happen 
in  two  ways.  For  sometimes  one  thing  is  predicated  of 
many  in  one  common  ratio,  as  animal  of  horse  and  ox :  and 
sometimes  one  thing  is  predicated  of  many  according  to 
priority  and  posteriority,  as  being  of  substance  and  accident. 

*    TO  €TTl€lK€S. 


171  EQUITY  Q.i  20.  Art.  2 

Accordingly,  epikeia  is  a  part  of  justice  taken  in  a  general 
sense,  for  it  is  a  kind  of  justice,  as  the  Philosopher  states 
{Ethic,  v.  10).  Wherefore  it  is  evident  that  epikeia  is  a  sub- 
jective part  of  justice;  and  justice  is  predicated  of  it  with 
priority  to  being  predicated  of  legal  justice,  since  legal  justice 
is  subject  to  the  direction  of  epikeia.  Hence  epikeia  is  by 
way  of  being  a  higher  rule  of  human  actions. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Epikeia  corresponds  properly  to  legal  justice, 
and  in  one  way  is  contained  under  it,  and  in  another  way 
exceeds  it.  For  if  legal  justice  denotes  that  which  complies 
with  the  law,  whether  as  regards  the  letter  of  the  law,  or  as 
regards  the  intention  of  the  lawgiver,  which  is  of  more 
account,  then  epikeia  is  the  more  important  part  of  legal 
justice.  But  if  legal  justice  denote  merely  that  which  com- 
plies with  the  law  with  regard  to  the  letter,  then  epikeia  is  a 
part  not  of  legal  justice  but  of  justice  in  its  general  accepta- 
tion, and  is  condivided  with  legal  justice,  as  exceeding  it. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  the  Philosopher  states  {Ethic,  v.  10), 
epikeia  is  better  than  a  certain,  namely,  legal,  justice,  which 
observes  the  letter  of  the  law :  yet  since  it  is  itself  a  kind  of 
justice,  it  is  not  better  than  all  justice. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  It  belongs  to  epikeia  to  moderate  something, 
namely,  the  observance  of  the  letter  of  the  law.  But 
modesty,  which  is  reckoned  a  part  of  temperance,  moderates 
man's  outward  life — for  instance,  in  his  deportment,  dress, 
or  the  like.  Possibly  also  the  term  eirie'tKeia  is  applied  in 
Greek  by  a  similitude  to  all  kinds  of  moderation. 


QUESTION  CXXI. 

OF  PIETY. 

{In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  gift  that  corresponds  to  justice; 
namely,  piety.  Under  this  head  there  are  two  points  of 
inquiry :  (i)  Whether  it  is  a  gift  of  the  Holy  Ghost  ? 
(2)  Which  of  the  beatitudes  and  fruits  corresponds  to  it  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  piety  is  a  gift  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  piety  is  not  a  gift.  For  the  gifts 
differ  from  the  virtues,  as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXVIII., 
A.  1).  But  piety  is  a  virtue,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CI.,  A.  3). 
Therefore  piety  is  not  a  gift. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  gifts  are  more  excellent  than  the 
virtues,  above  all  the  moral  virtues,  as  stated  above  (Q. 
LXVIII.,  A.  8).  Now  among  the  parts  of  justice  re- 
ligion is  greater  than  piety.  Therefore  if  any  part  of  justice 
is  to  be  accounted  a  gift,  it  seems  that  religion  should  be  a 
gift  rather  than  piety. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  gifts  and  their  acts  remain  in  heaven, 
as  stated  above  (I.-II.,  Q.  LXVIII.,  A.  6).  But  the  act  of 
piety  cannot  remain  in  heaven :  for  Gregory  says  {Moral,  i.) 
that  piety  fills  the  inmost  recesses  of  the  heart  with  works  of 
mercy:  and  so  there  will  be  no  piety  in  heaven  since  there  will 
be  no  unhappiness.*     Therefore  piety  is  not  a  gift. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  reckoned  among  the  gifts  in  the 
eleventh  chapter  of  Isaias  {verse  2:  Douay, — godliness).^ 

*  Cf.  Q.  XXX.  A.  1.  j  Cf.  Q-  LII.  A.  4,  footnote. 

172 


173  PIETY  0. 121.  Art  i 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXVIII.,  A.  i: 
Q.  LXIX.,  AA.  i,  3),  the  gifts  of  the  Holy  Ghost  are  habitual 
dispositions  of  the  soul,  rendering  it  amenable  to  the  motion 
of  the  Holy  Ghost.  Now  the  Holy  Ghost  moves  us  to  this 
effect  among  others,  of  having  a  filial  affection  towards  God, 
according  to  Rom.  viii.  15,  You  have  received  the  spirit  of 
adoption  of  sons,  whereby  we  cry :  Abba  (Father).  And  since 
it  belongs  properly  to  piety  to  pay  duty  and  worship  to  one's 
father,  it  follows  that  piety,  whereby,  at  the  Holy  Ghost's 
instigation,  we  pay  worship  and  duty  to  God  as  our  Father, 
is  a  gift  of  the  Holy  Ghost. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  piety  that  pays  duty  and  worship  to 
a  father  in  the  flesh  is  a  virtue :  but  the  piety  that  is  a  gift 
pays  this  to  God  as  Father. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  To  pay  worship  to  God  as  Creator,  as  religion 
does,  is  more  excellent  than  to  pay  worship  to  one's  father 
in  the  flesh,  as  the  piety  that  is  a  virtue  does.  But  to  pay 
worship  to  God  as  Father  is  yet  more  excellent  than  to 
pay  worship  to  God  as  Creator  and  Lord.  Wherefore  religion 
is  greater  than  the  virtue  of  piety :  while  the  gift  of  piety  is 
greater  than  religion. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  by  the  virtue  of  piety  man  pays  duty  and 
worship  not  only  to  his  father  in  the  flesh,  but  also  to  all 
his  kindred  on  account  of  their  being  related  to  his  father, 
so  by  the  gift  of  piety  he  pays  worship  and  duty  not  only  to 
God,  but  also  to  all  men  on  account  of  their  relationship  to 
God.  Hence  it  belongs  to  piety  to  honour  the  saints,  and 
not  to  contradict  the  Scriptures  whether  one  understands 
them  or  not,  as  Augustine  says  (De  Doctr.  Christ,  ii.).  Con- 
sequently it  also  assists  those  who  are  in  a  state  of  unhappi- 
ness.  And  although  this  act  has  no  place  in  heaven, 
especially  after  the  Day  of  Judgement,  yet  piety  will  exer- 
cise its  principal  act,  which  is  to  revere  God  with  filial 
affection:  for  it  is  then  above  all  that  this  act  will  be  ful- 
filled, according  to  Wis.  v.  5,  Behold  how  they  are  numbered 
among  the  children  of  God.  The  saints  will  also  mutually 
honour  one  another.  Now,  however,  before  the  Judgement 
Day,  the  saints  have  pity  on  those  also  who  are  living  in 
this  unhappy  state. 


Q.  i2i.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  174 


Second  Article. 

whether  the  second  beatitude,  "  blessed  are  the 
meek,"  corresponds  to  the  gift  of  piety  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  second  beatitude,  Blessed 
are  the  meek,  does  not  correspond  to  the  gift  of  piety.  For 
piety  is  the  gift  corresponding  to  justice,  to  which  rather 
belongs  the  fourth  beatitude,  Blessed  are  they  that  hunger  and 
thirst  after  justice,  or  the  fifth  beatitude,  Blessed  are  the 
merciful,  since,  as  stated  above  (A.  1,  Obj.  3),  the  works  of 
mercy  belong  to  piety.  Therefore  the  second  beatitude 
does  not  pertain  to  the  gift  of  piety. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  gift  of  piety  is  directed  by  the  gift 
of  knowledge,  which  is  united  to  it  in  the  enumeration  of 
the  gifts  (Isa.  xi.).  Now  direction  and  execution  extend 
to  the  same  matter.  Since,  then,  the  third  beatitude,  Blessed 
are  they  that  mourn,  corresponds  to  the  gift  of  knowledge, 
it  seems  that  the  second  beatitude  corresponds  to  piety. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  fruits  correspond  to  the  beatitudes 
and  gifts,  as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXX.,  A.  2).  Now 
among  the  fruits,  goodness  and  benignity  seem  to  agree  with 
piety  rather  than  mildness,  which  pertains  to  meekness. 
Therefore  the  second  beatitude  does  not  correspond  to  the 
gift  of  piety. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Serm.  Dom.  in  Monte 
i.) :  Piety  agrees  with  the  meek. 

I  answer  that,  In  adapting  the  beatitudes  to  the  gifts  a 
twofold  congruity  may  be  observed.  One  is  according  to 
the  order  in  which  they  are  given,  and  Augustine  seems  to 
have  followed  this :  wherefore  he  assigns  the  first  beatitude 
to  the  lowest  gift,  namely,  fear,  and  the  second  beatitude, 
Blessed  are  the  meek,  to  piety,  and  so  on.  Another  congruity 
may  be  observed  in  keeping  with  the  special  nature  of  each 
gift  and  beatitude.  In  this  way  one  must  adapt  the  beati- 
tudes to  the  gifts  according  to  their  objects  and  acts:  and 
thus  the  fourth  and  fifth  beatitudes  would  correspond  to 


175  PIETY  Q.  121.  Art.  2 

piety,  rather  than  the  second.  Yet  the  second  beatitude 
has  a  certain  congruity  with  piety,  inasmuch  as  meekness 
removes  the  obstacles  to  acts  of  piety. 

This  suffices  for  the  Reply  to  the  First  Objection. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Taking  the  beatitudes  and  gifts  according 
to  their  proper  natures,  the  same  beatitude  must  needs 
correspond  to  knowledge  and  piety:  but  taking  them  accord- 
ing to  their  order,  different  beatitudes  correspond  to  them, 
although  a  certain  congruity  may  be  observed,  as  stated 
above. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  the  fruits  goodness  and  benignity  may 
be  directly  ascribed  to  piety;  and  mildness  indirectly  in  so 
far  as  it  removes  obstacles  to  acts  of  piety,  as  stated  above. 


QUESTION  CXXII. 

OF  THE  PRECEPTS  OF  JUSTICE. 

(In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  precepts  of  justice,  under  which 
head  there  are  six  points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether  the  precepts 
of  the  decalogue  are  precepts  of  justice  ?  (2)  Of  the  first 
precept  of  the  decalogue  :  (3)  Of  the  second:  (4)  Of  the 
third:  (5)  Of  the  fourth:  (6)  Of  the  other  six. 

First  Article. 

whether  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are 
precepts  of  justice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  I.  It  seems  that  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue 
are  not  precepts  of  justice.  For  the  intention  of  a  lawgiver 
is  to  make  the  citizens  virtuous  in  respect  of  every  virtue,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  ii.  1.  Wherefore,  according  to  Ethic,  v.  1,  the 
law  prescribes  about  all  acts  of  all  virtues.  Now  the  precepts 
of  the  decalogue  are  the  first  principles  of  the  whole  Divine 
Law.  Therefore  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  do  not  per- 
tain to  justice  alone. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  It  would  seem  that  to  justice  belong 
especially  the  judicial  precepts,  which  are  condivided  with 
the  moral  precepts,  as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  XCIX.,  A.  4). 
But  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  moral  precepts,  as 
stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  C,  A.  3).  Therefore  the  precepts 
of  the  decalogue  are  not  precepts  of  justice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  Law  contains  chiefly  precepts  about 
acts  of  justice  regarding  the  common  good,  for  instance  about 
public  officers  and  the  like.     But  there  is  no  mention  of 

176 


177  PRECEPTS  OF  JUSTICE        Q.  122.  Art.  i 

these  in  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue.  Therefore  it  seems 
that  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  do  not  properly  belong 
to  justice. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  The  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  divided 
into  two  tables,  corresponding  to  the  love  of  God  and  the 
love  of  our  neighbour,  both  of  which  regard  the  virtue  of 
charity.  Therefore  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  belong  to 
charity  rather  than  to  justice. 

On  the  contrary,  Seemingly  justice  is  the  sole  virtue  whereby 
we  are  directed  to  another.  Now  we  are  directed  to  another 
by  all  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue,  as  is  evident  if  one  con- 
sider each  of  them.  Therefore  all  the  precepts  of  the  deca- 
logue pertain  to  justice. 

/  answer  that,  The  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  the  first 
principles  of  the  Law:  and  the  natural  reason  assents  to 
them  at  once,  as  to  principles  that  are  most  evident.  Now 
it  is  altogether  evident  that  the  notion  of  duty,  which  is 
essential  to  a  precept,  appears  in  justice,  which  is  of  one 
towards  another.  Because  in  those  matters  that  relate  to 
himself  it  would  seem  at  a  glance  that  man  is  master  of  him- 
self, and  that  he  may  do  as  he  likes :  whereas  in  matters  that 
refer  to  another  it  appears  manifestly  that  a  man  is  under 
obligation  to  render  to  another  that  which  is  his  due. 
Hence  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  must  needs  pertain  to 
justice.  Wherefore  the  first  three  precepts  are  about  acts 
of  religion,  which  is  the  chief  part  of  justice;  the  fourth 
precept  is  about  acts  of  piety,  which  is  the  second  part  of 
justice;  and  the  six  remaining  are  about  justice  commonly 
so  called,  which  is  observed  among  equals. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  intention  of  the  law  is  to  make  all  men 
virtuous,  but  in  a  certain  order,  namely,  by  first  of  all 
giving  them  precepts  about  those  things  where  the  notion 
of  duty  is  most  manifest,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  judicial  precepts  are  determinations 
of  the  moral  precepts,  in  so  far  as  these  are  directed  to  one's 
neighbour,  just  as  the  ceremonial  precepts  are  determinations 
of  the  moral  precepts  in  so  far  as  these  are  directed  to  God. 
Hence  neither  precepts  are  contained  in  the  decalogue :  and 

II.  ii.  4.  12 


Q.  122.  Art.  2    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  178 

yet  they  are  determinations  of  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue, 
and  therefore  pertain  to  justice. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Thing?  that  concern  the  common  good 
must  needs  be  administered  in  different  ways  according  to 
the  difference  of  men.  Hence  they  were  to  be  given  a 
place  not  among  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue,  but  among 
the  judicial  precepts. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  The  precepts  of  the  decalogue  pertain  to 
charity  as  their  end,  according  to  1  Tim.  i.  5,  The  end  of  the 
commandment  is  charity:  but  they  belong  to  justice,  inasmuch 
as  they  refer  immediately  to  acts  of  justice. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  first  precept  of  the  decalogue 
is  fittingly  expressed  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  first  precept  of  the  deca- 
logue is  unfittingly  expressed.  For  man  is  more  bound 
to  God  than  to  his  father  in  the  flesh,  according  to  Heb.  xii.  9, 
How  much  more  shall  we  (Vulg., — shall  we  not  much  more) 
obey  the  Father  of  spirits  and  live  ?  Now  the  precept  of 
piety,  whereby  man  honours  his  father,  is  expressed  affirma- 
tively in  these  words:  Honour  thy  father  and  thy  mother. 
Much  more,  therefore,  should  the  first  precept  of  religion, 
whereby  all  honour  God,  be  expressed  affirmatively,  espe- 
cially as  affirmation  is  naturally  prior  to  negation. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  first  precept  of  the  decalogue  per- 
tains to  religion,  as  stated  above  (A.  1).  Now  religion, 
since  it  is  one  virtue,  has  one  act.  Yet  in  the  first  precept 
three  acts  are  forbidden :  since  we  read  first :  Thou  shalt  not 
have  strange  gods  before  Me;  secondly,  Thou  shalt  not  make 
to  thyself  any  graven  thing ;  and  thirdly,  Thou  shalt  not  adore 
them  nor  serve  them.  Therefore  the  first  precept  is  unfit- 
tingly expressed. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  (De  decern  chord,  ix.)  that 
the  first  precept  forbids  the  sin  of  superstition.  But  there  are 
many  wicked  superstitions  besides  idolatry,  as  stated  above 


179  PRECEPTS  OF  JUSTICE        Q.i22.Art.2 

(Q.  XCIL,  A.  2).  Therefore  it  was  insufficient  to  forbid 
idolatry  alone. 

On  the  contrary,  stands  the  authority  of  Scripture. 

/  answer  that,  It  pertains  to  law  to  make  men  good,  where- 
fore it  behoved  the  precepts  of  the  Law  to  be  set  in  order 
according  to  the  order  of  generation,  the  order,  to  wit,  of 
man's  becoming  good.  Now  two  things  must  be  observed 
in  the  order  of  generation.  The  first  is  that  the  first  part 
is  the  first  thing  to  be  established;  thus  in  the  generation  of 
an  animal  the  first  thing  to  be  formed  is  the  heart,  and  in 
building  a  home  the  first  thing  to  be  set  up  is  the  foundation : 
and  in  the  goodness  of  the  soul  the  first  part  is  goodness  of 
the  will,  the  result  of  which  is  that  a  man  makes  good  use 
of  every  other  goodness.  Now  the  goodness  of  the  will 
depends  on  its  object,  which  is  its  end.  Wherefore  since 
man  was  to  be  directed  to  virtue  by  means  of  the  Law,  the 
first  thing  necessary  was,  as  it  were,  to  lay  the  foundation 
of  religion,  whereby  man  is  duly  directed  to  God,  Who  is 
the  last  end  of  man's  will. 

The  second  thing  to  be  observed  in  the  order  of  genera- 
tion is  that  in  the  first  place  contraries  and  obstacles  have 
to  be  removed.  Thus  the  farmer  first  purifies  the  soil,  and 
afterwards  sows  his  seed,  according  to  Jerem.  iv.  3,  Break 
up  anew  your  fallow  ground,  and  sow  not  upon  thorns.  Hence 
it  behoved  man,  first  of  all  to  be  instructed  in  religion,  so  as 
to  remove  the  obstacles  to  true  religion.  Now  the  chief 
obstacle  to  religion  is  for  man  to  adhere  to  a  false  god,  accord- 
ing to  Matth.  vi.  24,  You  cannot  serve  God  and  mammon. 
Therefore  in  the  first  precept  of  the  Law  the  worship  of 
false  gods  is  excluded. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  In  point  of  fact  there  is  one  affirmative 
precept  about  religion,  namely:  Remember  that  thou  keep 
holy  the  Sabbath  Day.  Still  the  negative  precepts  had  to  be 
given  first,  so  that  by  their  means  the  obstacles  to  religion 
might  be  removed.  For  though  affirmation  naturally  pre- 
cedes negation,  yet  in  the  process  of  generation  negation, 
whereby  obstacles  are  removed,  comes  first,  as  stated  in 
the  Article.     Especially  is  this  true  in  matters  concerning 


Q.  122.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  180 

God,  where  negation  is  preferable  to  affirmation,  on  account 
of  our  insufficiency,  as  Dionysius  observes  (Div.  Nom.  ii.) 

Reply  Obj.  2.  People  worshipped  strange  gods  in  two 
ways.  For  some  served  certain  creatures  as  gods  without 
having  recourse  to  images.  Hence  Varro  says  that  for  a 
long  time  the  ancient  Romans  worshipped  gods  without  using 
images:  and  this  worship  is  first  forbidden  by  the  words, 
Thou  shalt  not  have  strange  gods.  Among  others  the  worship 
of  false  gods  was  observed  by  using  certain  images:  and  so 
the  very  making  of  images  was  fittingly  forbidden  by  the 
words,  Thou  shalt  not  make  to  thyself  any  graven  thing,  as  also 
the  worship  of  those  same  images,  by  the  words,  Thou  shalt 
not  adore  them,  etc. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  All  other  kinds  of  superstition  proceed  from 
some  compact,  tacit  or  explicit,  with  the  demons;  hence  all 
are  understood  to  be  forbidden  by  the  words,  Thou  shalt  not 
have  strange  gods. 

Third  Article. 

whether  the  second  precept  of  the  decalogue 
is  fittingly  expressed  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  second  precept  of  the  deca- 
logue is  unfittingly  expressed.  For  this  precept,  Thou  shalt 
not  take  the  name  of  thy  God  in  vain  is  thus  explained  by  a 
gloss  on  Exod.  xx.  7:  Thou  shalt  not  deem  the  Son  of  God  to 
be  a  creature,  so  that  it  forbids  an  error  against  faith.  Again, 
a  gloss  on  the  words  of  Deut.  v.  11,  Thou  shalt  not  take  the 
name  of  .  .  .  thy  God  in  vain,  adds,  i.e.  by  giving  the  name  of 
God  to  wood  or  stone,  as  though  they  forbade  a  false  confes- 
sion of  faith,  which,  like  error,  is  an  act  of  unbelief.  Now 
unbelief  precedes  superstition,  as  faith  precedes  religion. 
Therefore  this  precept  should  have  preceded  the  first, 
whereby  superstition  is  forbidden. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  name  of  God  is  taken  for  many 
purposes — for  instance,  those  of  praise,  of  working  miracles, 
and  generally  speaking  in  conjunction  with  all  we  say  or  do, 
according  to  Col.  iii.  17,  All  whatsoever  you  do  in  word  or  in 


181  PRECEPTS  OF  JUSTICE         Q.  122.  Art.  3 

work  .  .  .  do  ye  in  the  name  of  the  Lord.  Therefore  the  precept 
forbidding  the  taking  of  God's  name  in  vain  seems  to  be 
more  universal  than  the  precept  forbidding  superstition, 
and  thus  should  have  preceded  it. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  A  gloss  on  Exod.  xx.  7  expounds  the 
precept,  Thou  shalt  not  take  the  name  of .  .  .  thy  God  in  vain, 
namely,  by  swearing  to  nothing.  Hence  this  precept  would 
seem  to  forbid  useless  swearing,  that  is  to  say,  swearing 
without  judgement.  But  false  swearing,  which  is  without 
truth,  and  unjust  swearing,  which  is  without  justice,  are 
much  more  grievous.  Therefore  this  precept  should  rather 
have  forbidden  them. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Blasphemy  or  any  word  or  deed  that  is 
an  insult  to  God  is  much  more  grievous  than  perjury.  There- 
fore blasphemy  and  other  like  sins  should  rather  have  been 
forbidden  by  this  precept. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  God's  names  are  many.  Therefore  it 
should  not  have  been  said  indefinitely:  Thou  shalt  not  take 
the  name  of  .  .  .  thy  God  in  vain. 

On  the  contrary  stands  the  authority  of  Scripture. 

/  answer  that,  In  one  who  is  being  instructed  in  virtue 
it  is  necessary  to  remove  obstacles  to  true  religion  before 
establishing  him  in  true  religion.  Now  a  thing  is  opposed 
to  true  religion  in  two  ways.  First,  by  excess,  when,  to 
wit,  that  which  belongs  to  religion  is  given  to  others  than  to 
whom  it  is  due,  and  this  pertains  to  superstition.  Secondly, 
by  lack,  as  it  were,  of  reverence,  when,  to  wit,  God  is  con- 
temned, and  this  pertains  to  the  vice  of  irreligion,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XCVTL,  in  the  preamble,  and  in  the  Article  that 
follows).  Now  superstition  hinders  religion  by  preventing 
man  from  acknowledging  God  so  as  to  worship  Him :  and 
when  a  man's  mind  is  engrossed  in  some  undue  worship, 
he  cannot  at  the  same  time  give  due  worship  to  God,  accord- 
ing to  Isa.  xxviii.  20,  The  bed  is  straitened,  so  that  one  must 
fall  out,  i.e.  either  the  true  God  or  a  false  god  must  fall  out 
from  man's  heart,  and  a  short  covering  cannot  cover  both. 
On  the  other  hand,  irreligion  hinders  religion  by  preventing 
man  from  honouring  God  after  he  has  acknowledged  Him. 


Q.  122.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  182 

Now  one  must  first  of  all  acknowledge  God  with  a  view  to 
worship,  before  honouring  Him  we  have  acknowledged. 

For  this  reason  the  precept  forbidding  superstition  is 
placed  before  the  second  precept,  which  forbids  perjury  that 
pertains  to  irreligion. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  These  expositions  are  mystical.  The  literal 
explanation  is  that  which  is  given  Deut.  v.  n :  Thou  shall 
not  take  the  name  of  .  .  .  thy  God  in  vain,  namely,  by  swearing 
on  that  which  is  not* 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  precept  does  not  forbid  all  taking  of 
the  name  of  God,  but  properly  the  taking  of  God's  name  in 
confirmation  of  a  man's  word  by  way  of  an  oath,  because 
men  are  wont  to  take  God's  name  more  frequently  in  this 
way.  Nevertheless  we  may  understand  that  in  consequence 
all  inordinate  taking  of  the  Divine  name  is  forbidden  by 
this  precept :  and  it  is  in  this  sense  that  we  are  to  take  the 
explanation  quoted  in  the  First  Objection. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  To  swear  to  nothing  means  to  swear  to  that 
which  is  not.  This  pertains  to  false  swearing,  which  is 
chiefly  called  perjury,  as  stated  above  (Q.XCVIII.,A.  i,ad^). 
For  when  a  man  swears  to  that  which  is  false,  his  swearing 
is  vain  in  itself,  since  it  is  not  supported  by  the  truth.  On 
the  other  hand,  when  a  man  swears  without  judgement, 
through  levity,  if  he  swear  to  the  truth,  there  is  no  vanity 
on  the  part  of  the  oath  itself,  but  only  on  the  part  of  the 
swearer. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Just  as  when  we  instruct  a  man  in  some 
science,  we  begin  b}/  putting  before  him  certain  general 
maxims,  even  so  the  Law,  which  forms  man  to  virtue  by 
instructing  him  in  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue,  which  are 
the  first  of  all  precepts,  gave  expression,  by  prohibition  or 
by  command,  to  those  things  which  are  of  most  common 
occurrence  in  the  course  of  human  life.  Hence  the  precepts 
of  the  decalogue  include  the  prohibition  of  perjury,  which  is 
of  more  frequent  occurrence  than  blasphemy,  since  man  does 
not  fall  so  often  into  the  latter  sin. 

*  Vulg., — for  he  shall  not  be  unpunished  that  taketh  His  name  upon 
a  vain  thing. 


183  PRECEPTS  OF  JUSTICE        Q.  122.  Art.  4 

Reply  Obj.  5.  Reverence  is  due  to  the  Divine  names  on 
the  part  of  the  thing  signified,  which  is  one,  and  not  on  the 
part  of  the  signifying  words,  which  are  many.  Hence  it  is 
expressed  in  the  singular :  Thou  shalt  not  take  the  name  of .  .  . 
thy  God  in  vain:  since  it  matters  not  in  which  of  God's  names 
perjury  is  committed. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  third  precept  of  the  decalogue,  concern- 
ing the  hallowing  of  the  sabbath,  is  fittingly 
expressed  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  third  precept  of  the  deca- 
logue, concerning  the  hallowing  of  the  Sabbath,  is  unfittingly 
expressed.  For  this,  understood  spiritually,  is  a  general 
precept :  since  Bede  in  commenting  on  Luke  xiii.  14,  The  ruler 
of  the  synagogue  being  angry  that  He  had  healed  on  the  Sabbath, 
says  {Comment,  iv.):  The  Law  forbids,  not  to  heal  man  on 
the  Sabbath,  but  to  do  servile  works,  i.e.  to  burden  oneself  with 
sin.  Taken  literally  it  is  a  ceremonial  precept,  for  it  is 
written  (Exod.  xxxi.  13) :  See  that  you  keep  My  Sabbath : 
because  it  is  a  sign  between  Me  and  you  in  your  generations. 
Now  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  both  spiritual  and 
moral.  Therefore  it  is  unfittingly  placed  among  the  precepts 
of  the  decalogue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  ceremonial  precepts  of  the  Law 
contain  sacred  things,  sacrifices,  sacraments  and  observances, 
as  stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  CI.,  A.  4).  Now  sacred  things 
comprised  not  only  sacred  days,  but  also  sacred  places  and 
sacred  vessels,  and  so  on.  Moreover,  there  were  many  sacred 
days  other  than  the  Sabbath.  Therefore  it  was  unfitting 
to  omit  all  other  ceremonial  observances  and  to  mention 
only  that  of  the  Sabbath. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Whoever  breaks  a  precept  of  the  deca- 
logue, sins.  But  in  the  Old  Law  some  who  broke  the  obser- 
vances of  the  Sabbath  did  not  sin — for  instance,  those  who 
circumcised  their  sons  on  the  eighth  day,  and  the  priests 


Q.  122.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  184 

who  worked  in  the  temple  on  the  Sabbath.  Also  Elias 
(3  Kings  xix.),  who  journeyed  for  forty  days  unto  the  mount 
of  God,  Horeb,  must  have  travelled  oh  a  Sabbath :  the  priests 
also  who  carried  the  ark  of  the  Lord  for  seven  days,  as 
related  in  Josue  vii.,  must  be  understood  to  have  carried  it 
on  a  Sabbath.  Again  it  is  written  (Luke  xiii.  15) :  Doth  not 
every  one  of  you  on  the  Sabbath  day  loose  his  ox  or  his  ass  .  .  . 
and  lead  them  to  water  ?  Therefore  it  is  unfittingly  placed 
among  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  The  precepts  of  the  decalogue  have  to 
be  observed  also  under  the  New  Law.  Yet  in  the  New  Law 
this  precept  is  not  observed,  neither  in  the  point  of  the 
Sabbath  day,  nor  as  to  the  Lord's  day,  on  which  men  cook 
their  food,  travel,  fish,  and  do  many  like  things.  There- 
fore the  precept  of  the  observance  of  the  Sabbath  is  un- 
fittingly expressed. 

On  the  contrary  stands  the  authority  of  Scripture. 

I  answer  that,  The  obstacles  to  true  religion  being  removed 
by  the  first  and  second  precepts  of  the  decalogue,  as  stated 
above  (AA.  2,  3),  it  remained  for  the  third  precept  to  be 
given  whereby  man  is  established  in  true  religion.  Now  it 
belongs  to  religion  to  give  worship  to  God:  and  just  as  the 
Divine  scriptures  teach  us  the  interior  worship  under  the  guise 
of  certain  corporal  similitudes,  so  is  external  worship  given 
to  God  under  the  guise  of  sensible  signs.  And  since  for 
the  most  part  man  is  induced  to  pay  interior  worship,  con- 
sisting in  prayer  and  devotion,  by  the  interior  prompting 
of  the  Holy  Ghost,  a  precept  of  the  Law  was  necessary  re- 
specting the  exterior  worship  that  consists  in  sensible  signs. 
Now  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are,  so  to  speak,  first  and 
common  principles  of  the  Law,  and  consequently  the  third 
precept  of  the  decalogue  prescribes  the  exterior  worship  of 
God  as  the  sign  of  a  universal  boon  that  concerns  all.  This 
universal  boon  was  the  work  of  the  Creation  of  the  world, 
from  which  work  God  is  stated  to  have  rested  on  the  seventh 
day :  and  in  sign  of  this  we  are  commanded  to  keep  holy  the 
seventh  day — that  is,  to  set  it  aside  as  a  day  to  be  given  to  God. 
Hence  after  the  precept  about  the  hallowing  of  the  Sabbath 


185  PRECEPTS  OF  JUSTICE        Q.  122.  Art.  4 

the  reason  for  it  is  given:  For  in  six  days  the  Lord  made 
heaven  and  earth  .  .  .  and  rested  on  the  seventh  day. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  precept  about  hallowing  the  Sabbath, 
understood  literally,  is  partly  moral  and  partly  ceremonial. 
It  is  a  moral  precept  in  the  point  of  commanding  man  to  set 
aside  a  certain  time  to  be  given  to  Divine  things.  For  there 
is  in  man  a  natural  inclination  to  set  aside  a  certain  time  for 
each  necessary  thing,  such  as  refreshment  of  the  body,  sleep, 
and  so  forth.  Hence  according  to  the  dictate  of  reason, 
man  sets  aside  a  certain  time  for  spiritual  refreshment,  by 
which  man's  mind  is  refreshed  in  God.  And  thus  to  have  a 
certain  time  set  aside  for  occupying  oneself  with  Divine 
things  is  the  matter  of  a  moral  precept.  But,  in  so  far  as 
this  precept  specializes  the  time  as  a  sign  representing  the 
Creation  of  the  world,  it  is  a  ceremonial  precept.  Again, 
it  is  a  ceremonial  precept  in  its  allegorical  signification,  as 
representative  of  Christ's  rest  in  the  tomb  on  the  seventh 
day :  as  also  in  its  moral  signification,  as  representing  cessation 
from  all  sinful  acts,  and  the  mind's  rest  in  God,  in  which  sense, 
too,  it  is  a  general  precept.  Again,  it  is  a  ceremonial  precept 
in  its  analogical  signification,  as  foreshadowing  the  enjoy- 
ment of  God  in  heaven.  Hence  the  precept  about  hallowing 
the  Sabbath  is  placed  among  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue, 
as  a  moral,  but  not  as  a  ceremonial  precept. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  other  ceremonies  of  the  Law  are  signs 
of  certain  particular  Divine  works:  but  the  observance  of 
the  Sabbath  is  representative  of  a  general  boon,  namely, 
the  production  of  all  creatures.  Hence  it  was  fitting  that 
it  should  be  placed  among  the  general  precepts  of  the  deca- 
logue, rather  than  any  other  ceremonial  precept  of  the  Law. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Two  things  are  to  be  observed  in  the  hallow- 
ing of  the  Sabbath.  One  of  these  is  the  end:  and  this  is 
that  man  occupy  himself  with  Divine  things,  and  is  signified 
in  the  words :  Remember  that  thou  keep  holy  the  Sabbath  day. 
For  in  the  Law  those  things  are  said  to  be  holy  which  are 
applied  to  the  Divine  worship.  The  other  thing  is  cessation 
from  work,  and  is  signified  in  the  words  (Exod.  xx.  n),  On 
the  seventh  day  .  .  .  thou  shalt  do  no  work.     The  kind  of  work 


Q.  i22.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  186 

meant  appears  from  Levit.  xxiii.  3,  You  shall  do  no  servile* 
work  on  that  day.  Now  servile  work  is  so  called  from  servi- 
tude: and  servitude  is  threefold.  One,  whereby  man  is  the 
servant  of  sin,  according  to  John  viii.  34,  Whosoever  com- 
mitteth  sin  is  the  servant  of  sin,  and  in  this  sense  all  sinful 
acts  are  servile.  Another  servitude  is  whereby  one  man 
serves  another.  Now  one  man  serves  another  not  with  his 
mind  but  with  his  body,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CIV.,  AA.  5,  6, 
ad  1).  Wherefore  in  this  respect  those  works  are  called 
servile  whereby  one  man  serves  another.  The  third  is  the 
servitude  of  God;  and  in  this  way  the  work  of  worship,  which 
pertains  to  the  service  of  God,  may  be  called  a  servile  work. 
In  this  sense  servile  work  is  not  forbidden  on  the  Sabbath 
day,  because  that  would  be  contrary  to  the  end  of  the 
Sabbath  observance:  since  man  abstains  from  other  works 
on  the  Sabbath  day  in  order  that  he  may  occupy  himself 
with  works  connected  with  God's  service.  For  this  reason, 
according  to  John  vii.  23,  a  man'f  receives  circumcision  on  the 
Sabbath  day,  that  the  law  of  Moses  may  not  be  broken:  and  for 
this  reason  too  we  read  (Matth.  xii.  5),  that  on  the  Sabbath 
days  the  priests  in  the  temple  break  the  Sabbath,  i.e.  do  corporal 
works  on  the  Sabbath,  and  are  without  blame.  Accordingly, 
the  priests  in  carrying  the  ark  on  the  Sabbath  did  not  break 
the  precept  of  the  Sabbath  observance.  In  like  manner  it 
is  not  contrary  to  the  observance  of  the  Sabbath  to  exercise 
any  spiritual  act,  such  as  teaching  by  word  or  writing. 
Wherefore  a  gloss  on  Num.  xxviii.  says  that  smiths  and  like 
craftsmen  rest  on  the  Sabbath  day,  but  the  reader  or  teacher  of 
the  Divine  law  does  not  cease  from  his  work.  Yet  he  profanes 
not  the  Sabbath,  even  as  the  priests  in  the  temple  break  the 
Sabbath,  and  are  without  blame. 

On  the  other  hand,  those  works  that  are  called  servile  in 
the  first  or  second  way  are  contrary  to  the  observance  of 
the  Sabbath,  in  so  far  as  they  hinder  man  from  applying 
himself  to  Divine  things.  And  since  man  is  hindered  from 
applying  himself  to  Divine  things  rather  by  sinful  than  by 

*  Vulg., — You  shall  do  no  work  on  that  day. 
t  Vulg., — If  a  man,  etc. 


187  PRECEPTS  OF  JUSTICE        Q.  122.  Art.  4 

lawful  albeit  corporal  works,  it  follows  that  to  sin  on  a  feast 
day  is  more  against  this  precept  than  to  do  some  other  but 
lawful  bodily  work.  Hence  Augustine  says  (De  decern 
chord,  iii.):  It  would  be  better  if  the  Jew  did  some  useful  work 
on  his  farm  than  spent  his  time  seditiously  in  the  theatre :  and 
their  womenfolk  would  do  better  to  be  making  linen  on  the 
Sabbath  than  to  be  dancing  lewdly  all  day  in  their  feasts  of  the 
new  moon.  It  is  not,  however,  against  this  precept  to  sin 
venially  on  the  Sabbath,  because  venial  sin  does  not  destroy 
holiness. 

Again,  corporal  works,  not  pertaining  to  the  spiritual 
worship  of  God,  are  said  to  be  servile  in  so  far  as  they  belong 
properly  to  servants;  while  they  are  not  said  to  be  servile, 
in  so  far  as  they  are  common  to  those  who  serve  and  those 
who  are  free.  Moreover,  everyone,  be  he  servant  or  free,  is 
bound  to  provide  necessaries  both  for  himself  and  for  his 
neighbour,  chiefly  in  respect  of  things  pertaining  to  the  well- 
being  of  the  body,  according  to  Prov.  xxiv.  11,  Deliver  them 
that  are  led  to  death:  secondarily  as  regards  avoiding  damage 
to  one's  property,  according  to  Deut.  xxii.  1,  Thou  shalt  not 
pass  by  if  thou  seest  thy  brother's  ox  or  his  sheep  go  astray,  but 
thou  shalt  bring  them  back  to  thy  brother.  Hence  a  corporal 
work  pertaining  to  the  preservation  of  one's  own  bodily 
well-being  does  not  profane  the  Sabbath :  for  it  is  not  against 
the  observance  of  the  Sabbath  to  eat  and  do  such  things  as 
preserve  the  health  of  the  body.  For  this  reason  the 
Machabees  did  not  profane  the  Sabbath  when  they  fought 
in  self-defence  on  the  Sabbath  day  (1  Machab.  ii.),  nor  Elias 
when  he  fled  from  the  face  of  Jezabel  on  the  Sabbath.  For 
this  same  reason  our  Lord  (Matth.  xii.  3)  excused  His  dis- 
ciples for  plucking  the  ears  of  corn  on  account  of  the  need 
which  they  suffered.  In  like  manner  a  bodily  work  that  is 
directed  to  the  bodily  well-being  of  another  is  not  contrary 
to  the  observance  of  the  Sabbath:  wherefore  it  is  written 
(John  vii.  23) :  Are  you  angry  at  Me  because  I  have  healed  the 
whole  man  on  the  Sabbath  day?  And  again,  a  bodily  work 
that  is  done  to  avoid  an  imminent  damage  to  some  external 
thing  does  not  profane  the  Sabbath,  wherefore  our  Lord 


Q.  122.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  188 

says  (Matth.  xii.  11):  What  man  shall  there  be  among  you, 
that  hath  one  sheep,  and  if  the  same  fall  into  a  pit  on  the 
Sabbath  day,  will  he  not  take  hold  on  it  and  lift  it  up  ? 

Reply  Obj.  4.  In  the  New  Law  the  observance  of  the  Lord's 
day  took  the  place  of  the  observance  of  the  Sabbath,  not 
by  virtue  of  the  precept  but  by  the  institution  of  the  Church 
and  the  custom  of  Christian  people.  For  this  observance 
is  not  figurative,  as  was  the  observance  of  the  Sabbath  in 
the  Old  Law.  Hence  the  prohibition  to  work  on  the  Lord's 
day  is  not  so  strict  as  on  the  Sabbath:  and  certain  works  are 
permitted  on  the  Lord's  day  which  were  forbidden  on  the 
Sabbath,  such  as  the  cooking  of  food  and  so  forth.  And 
again,  in  the  New  Law  dispensation  is  more  easily  granted 
than  in  the  Old,  in  the  matter  of  certain  forbidden  works, 
on  account  of  their  necessity,  because  the  figure  pertains  to 
the  protestation  of  truth,  which  it  is  unlawful  to  omit  even 
in  small  things;  while  works,  considered  in  themselves,  are 
changeable  in  point  of  place  and  time. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  the  fourth  precept,  about  honouring  one's 
parents,  is  fittingly  expressed  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  fourth  precept,  about 
honouring  one's  parents,  is  unfittingly  expressed.  For  this 
is  the  precept  pertaining  to  piety.  Now,  just  as  piety  is  a 
part  of  justice,  so  are  observance,  gratitude,  and  others  of 
which  we  have  spoken  (QQ.  CI.,  CIL,  seq.).  Therefore  it 
seems  that  there  should  not  have  been  given  a  special 
precept  of  piety,  as  none  is  given  regarding  the  others. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Piety  pays  worship  not  only  to  one's 
parents,  but  also  to  one's  country,  and  also  to  other  blood 
kindred,  and  to  the  well-wishers  of  our  country,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  CL,  AA.  1,  2).  Therefore  it  was  unfitting  for  this 
precept  to  mention  only  the  honouring  of  one's  father  and 
mother. 

Ob].  3.  Further,  We  owe  our  parents  not  merely  honour 


189  PRECEPTS  OF  JUSTICE        Q.  122.  Art.  5 

but  also  support.  Therefore  the  mere  honouring  of  one's 
parents  is  unfittingly  prescribed. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Sometimes  those  who  honour  their 
parents  die  young,  and  on  the  contrary  those  who  honour 
them  not  live  a  long  time.  Therefore  it  was  unfitting  to 
supplement  this  precept  with  the  promise,  That  thou  may  est 
be  long-lived  upon  earth. 

On  the  contrary  stands  the  authority  of  Scripture. 

/  answer  that,  The  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  directed 
to  the  love  of  God  and  of  our  neighour.  Now  to  our  parents, 
of  all  our  neighbours,  we  are  under  the  greatest  obligation. 
Hence,  immediately  after  the  precepts  directing  us  to  God, 
a  place  is  given  to  the  precept  directing  us  to  our  parents, 
who  are  the  particular  principle  of  our  being,  just  as  God  is 
the  universal  principle:  so  that  this  precept  has  a  certain 
affinity  to  the  precepts  of  the  First  Table. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CI.,  A.  2),  piety  directs 
us  to  pay  the  debt  due  to  our  parents,  a  debt  which  is  common 
to  all.  Hence,  since  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  general 
precepts,  they  ought  to  contain  some  reference  to  piety 
rather  than  to  the  other  parts  of  justice,  which  regard  some 
special  debt. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  debt  to  one's  parents  precedes  the  debt 
to  one's  kindred  and  country:  since  it  is  because  we  are  born 
of  our  parents  that  our  kindred  and  country  belong  to  us. 
Hence,  since  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  the  first 
precepts  of  the  Law,  they  direct  man  to  his  parents  rather 
than  to  his  country  and  other  kindred.  Nevertheless  this 
precept  of  honouring  our  parents  is  understood  to  command 
whatever  concerns  the  payment  of  debt  to  any  person,  as 
secondary  matter  included  in  the  principal  matter. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Reverential  honour  is  due  to  one's  parents 
as  such,  whereas  support  and  so  forth  are  due  to  them  acci- 
dentally, for  instance,  because  they  are  in  want,  in  slavery, 
or  the  like,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CI.,  A.  2).  And  since  that 
which  belongs  to  a  thing  by  nature  precedes  that  which  is 
accidental,  it  follows  that  among  the  first  precepts  of  the 
Law,  which  are  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue,  there  is  a 


Q.  122.  Art.  5    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  190 

special  precept  of  honouring  our  parents:  and  this  honour, 
as  a  kind  of  principle,  is  understood  to  comprise  support  and 
whatever  else  is  due  to  our  parents. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  A  long  life  is  promised  to  those  who  honour 
their  parents  not  only  as  to  the  life  to  come,  but  also  as  to 
the  present  life,  according  to  the  saying  of  the  Apostle 
(1  Tim.  iv.  8) :  Piety  (Douay, — Godliness)  is  -profitable  to  all 
things,  having  promise  of  the  life  that  now  is  and  of  that 
which  is  to  come.  And  with  reason.  Because  the  man  who 
is  grateful  for  a  favour  deserves,  with  a  certain  congruity, 
that  the  favour  should  be  continued  to  him,  and  he  who  is 
ungrateful  for  a  favour  deserves  to  lose  it.  Now  we  owe 
the  favour  of  bodily  life  to  our  parents  after  God :  wherefore 
he  that  honours  his  parents  deserves  the  prolongation  of 
his  life,  because  he  is  grateful  for  that  favour :  while  he  that 
honours  not  his  parents  deserves  to  be  deprived  of  life 
because  he  is  ungrateful  for  the  favour.  However,  present 
goods  or  evils  are  not  the  subject  of  merit  or  demerit  except 
in  so  far  as  they  are  directed  to  a  future  reward,  as  stated 
above  (I. -II.,  Q.  CXIV.,  A.  12),  wherefore  sometimes  in 
accordance  with  the  hidden  design  of  the  Divine  judgments, 
which  regard  chiefly  the  future  reward,  some,  who  are  dutiful 
to  their  parents,  are  sooner  deprived  of  life,  while  others,  who 
are  undutiful  to  their  parents,  live  longer. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  the  other  six  precepts  of  the  decalogue 
are  fittingly  expressed  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  other  six  precepts  of  the 
decalogue  are  unfittingly  expressed.  For  it  is  not  sufficient 
for  salvation  that  one  refrain  from  injuring  one's  neighbour; 
but  it  is  required  that  one  pay  one's  debts,  according  to 
Rom.  xiii.  7,  Render  .  .  .  to  all  men  their  dues.  Now  the  last 
six  precepts  merely  forbid  one  to  injure  one's  neighbour. 
Therefore  these  precepts  are  unfittingly  expressed. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  These  precepts  forbid  murder,  adultery, 


igi  PRECEPTS  OF  JUSTICE        Q.  122.  Art.  6 

stealing  and  bearing  false  witness.  But  many  other  injuries 
can  be  inflicted  on  one's  neighbour,  as  appears  from  those 
which  have  been  specified  above  (QQ.  LXXIL,  seq.).  There- 
fore it  seems  that  the  aforesaid  precepts  are  unfittingly 
expressed. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Concupiscence  may  be  taken  in  two  ways. 
First  as  denoting  an  act  of  the  will,  as  in  Wis.  vi.  21,  The  desire 
(concupiscentia)  of  wisdom  bringeth  to  the  everlasting  kingdom : 
secondly,  as  denoting  an  act  of  the  sensuality,  as  in  James 
iv.  1.,  From  whence  are  wars  and  contentions  among  you? 
Are  they  not  .  .  .from  your  concupiscences  which  war  in  your 
members  ?  Now  the  concupiscence  of  the  sensuality  is  not 
forbidden  by  a  precept  of  the  decalogue,  otherwise  first 
movements  would  be  mortal  sins,  as  they  would  be  against 
a  precept  of  the  decalogue.  Nor  is  the  concupiscence  of 
the  will  forbidden,  since  it  is  included  in  every  sin.  There- 
fore it  is  unfitting  for  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  to  include 
some  that  forbid  concupiscence. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Murder  is  a  more  grievous  sin  than 
adultery  or  theft.  But  there  is  no  precept  forbidding  the 
desire  of  murder.  Therefore  neither  was  it  fitting  to  have 
precepts  forbidding  the  desire  of  theft  and  of  adultery. 

On  the  contrary  stands  the  authority  of  Scripture. 

/  answer  that,  Just  as  by  the  parts  of  justice  a  man  pays 
that  which  is  due  to  certain  definite  persons,  to  whom  he  is 
bound  for  some  special  reason,  so  too  by  justice  properly 
so  called  he  pays  that  which  is  due  to  all  in  general.  Hence, 
after  the  three  precepts  pertaining  to  religion,  whereby  man 
pays  what  is  due  to  God,  and  after  the  fourth  precept  per- 
taining to  piety,  whereby  he  pays  what  is  due  to  his  parents 
— which  duty  includes  the  paying  of  all  that  is  due  for  any 
special  reason — it  was  necessary  in  due  sequence  to  give 
certain  precepts  pertaining  to  justice  properly  so  called, 
which  pays  to  all  indifferently  what  is  due  to  them. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Man  is  bound  towards  all  persons  in  general 
to  inflict  injury  on  no  one:  hence  the  negative  precepts, 
which  forbid  the  doing  of  those  injuries  that  can  be  inflicted 
on  one's  neighbour,  had  to  be  given  a  place,  as  general 


Q.  122.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  192 

precepts,  among  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue.  On  the 
other  hand,  the  duties  we  owe  to  our  neighbour  are  paid  in 
different  ways  to  different  people:  hence  it  did  not  behove 
to  include  affirmative  precepts  about  these  duties  among 
the  precepts  of  the  decalogue. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  All  other  injuries  that  are  inflicted  on  our 
neighbour  are  reducible  to  those  that  are  forbidden  by  these 
precepts,  as  taking  precedence  of  others  in  point  of  gener- 
ality and  importance.  For  all  injuries  that  are  inflicted  on 
the  person  of  our  neighbour  are  understood  to  be  forbidden 
under  the  head  of  murder  as  being  the  principal  of  all. 
Those  that  are  inflicted  on  a  person  connected  with  one's 
neighbour,  especially  by  way  of  lust,  are  understood  to  be 
forbidden  together  with  adultery:  those  that  come  under 
the  head  of  damage  done  to  property  are  understood  to  be 
forbidden  together  with  theft :  and  those  that  are  comprised 
under  speech,  such  as  detractions,  insults,  and  so  forth,  are 
understood  to  be  forbidden  together  with  the  bearing  of 
false  witness,  which  is  more  directly  opposed  to  justice. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  precepts  forbidding  concupiscence  do 
not  include  the  prohibition  of  first  movements  of  concupi- 
scence, that  do  not  go  farther  than  the  bounds  of  the  sen- 
suality. The  direct  object  of  their  prohibition  is  the  consent 
of  the  will,  which  is  directed  to  deed  or  pleasure. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Murder  in  itself  is  an  object  not  of  concu- 
piscence but  of  horror,  since  it  has  not  in  itself  the  aspect 
of  good.  On  the  other  hand,  adultery  has  the  aspect  of  a 
certain  kind  of  good,  i.e.  of  something  pleasurable,  and  theft 
has  an  aspect  of  good,  i.e.  of  something  useful:  and  good  of 
its  very  nature  has  the  aspect  of  something  concupiscible. 
Hence  the  concupiscence  of  theft  and  adulter}'  had  to  be 
forbidden  by  special  precepts,  but  not  the  concupiscence 
of  murder. 


QUESTION   CXXIII. 

OF   FORTITUDE. 

(In  Twelve  Articles.) 

After  considering  justice  we  must  in  due  sequence  consider 
fortitude.  We  must  (i)  consider  the  virtue  itself  of  for- 
titude;  (2)  its  parts;    (3)  the  gift  corresponding  thereto; 

(4)  the  precepts  that  pertain  to  it. 

Concerning  fortitude  three  things  have  to  be  considered: 
(1)  Fortitude  itself;  (2)  its  principal  act,  viz.  martyrdom; 
(3)  the  vices  opposed  to  fortitude. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  twelve  points  of  inquiry: 
(1)  Whether  fortitude  is  a  virtue  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  a 
special  virtue  ?  (3)  Whether  fortitude  is  only  about  fear 
and  daring  ?  (4)  Whether  it  is  only  about  fear  of  death  ? 

(5)  Whether  it  is  only  in  warlike  matters  ?  (6)  Whether 
endurance  is  its  chief  act  ?  (7)  Whether  its  action  is 
directed  to  its  own  good  ?  (8)  Whether  it  takes  pleasure 
in  its  own  action  ?  (9)  Whether  fortitude  deals  chiefly 
with  sudden  occurrences  ?  (10)  Whether  it  makes  use 
of  anger  in  its  action  ?  (n)  Whether  it  is  a  cardinal 
virtue  ?  (12)  Of  its  comparison  with  the  other  cardinal 
virtues. 

First  Article, 
whether  fortitude  is  a  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 
Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fortitude  is  not  a  virtue.     For 
the    Apostle   says    (2   Cor.  xii.  9) :    Virtue   is  perfected  in 
11.  ii.  4  193  13 


Q.  123.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  194 

infirmity.     But  fortitude  is  contrary  to  infirmity.     There- 
fore fortitude  is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  If  it  is  a  virtue,  it  is  either  theological, 
intellectual,  or  moral.  Now  fortitude  is  not  contained 
among  the  theological  virtues,  nor  among  the  intellectual 
virtues,  as  may  be  gathered  from  what  we  have  said  above 
(I.-IL,  Q.  LVIL,  A.  2;  LXII.,  A.  3).  Neither,  apparently, 
is  it  contained  among  the  moral  virtues,  since  according  to 
the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  hi.  7,  8):  Some  seem  to  be  brave 
through  ignorance;  or  through  experience,  as  soldiers,  both  of 
which  cases  seem  to  pertain  to  act  rather  than  to  moral 
virtue,  and  some  are  called  brave  on  account  of  certain  passions; 
for  instance,  on  account  of  fear  of  threats,  or  of  dishonour, 
or  again  on  account  of  sorrow,  anger,  or  hope.  But  moral 
virtue  does  not  act  from  passion  but  from  choice,  as  stated 
above  (I.-IL,  Q.  LV.,  A.  4).  Therefore  fortitude  is  not  a 
virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Human  virtue  resides  chiefly  in  the  soul, 
since  it  is  a  good  quality  of  the  mind,  as  stated  above  (loc.  cit.). 
But  fortitude,  seemingly,  resides  in  the  body,  or  at  least 
results  from  the  temperament  of  the  body.  Therefore  it 
seems  that  fortitude  is  not  a  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  (De  Morib.  Eccl.  xv.,  xxi.,  xxii.) 
numbers  fortitude  among  the  virtues. 

/  answer  that,  According  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  ii.  6) 
virtue  is  that  which  makes  its  subject  good,  and  renders  its 
work  good.  Hence  human  virtue,  of  which  we  are  speaking 
now,  is  that  which  makes  a  man  good,  and  renders  his  work 
good.  Now  man's  good  is  to  be  in  accordance  with  reason, 
according  to  Dionysius  (Div.  Nom.  iv.  22).  Wherefore  it 
belongs  to  human  virtue  to  make  man  good,  to  make  his 
work  accord  with  reason.  This  happens  in  three  ways: 
first,  by  rectifying  reason  itself,  and  this  is  done  by  the 
intellectual  virtues;  secondly,  by  establishing  the  rectitude 
of  reason  in  human  affairs,  and  this  belongs  to  justice; 
thirdly,  by  removing  the  obstacles  to  the  establishment 
of  this  rectitude  in  human  affairs.  Now  the  human  will  is 
hindered  in  two  ways  from  following  the  rectitude  of  reason. 


195  FORTITUDE  Q.  123.  Art.  i 

First,  through  being  drawn  by  some  object  of  pleasure  to 
something  other  than  what  the  rectitude  of  reason  requires ; 
and  this  obstacle  is  removed  by  the  virtue  of  temperance. 
Secondly,  through  the  will  being  disinclined  to  follow  that 
which  is  in  accordance  with  reason,  on  account  of  some 
difficulty  that  presents  itself.  In  order  to  remove  this 
obstacle  fortitude  of  the  mind  is  requisite,  whereby  to 
resist  the  aforesaid  difficulty,  even  as  a  man,  by  fortitude 
of  body,  overcomes  and  removes  bodily  obstacles. 

Hence  it  is  evident  that  fortitude  is  a  virtue,  in  so  far  as 
it  conforms  man  to  reason. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  virtue  of  the  soul  is  perfected,  not  in 
the  infirmity  of  the  soul,  but  in  the  infirmity  of  the  body, 
of  which  the  Apostle  was  speaking.  Now  it  belongs  to 
fortitude  of  the  mind  to  bear  bravely  with  infirmities  of 
the  flesh,  and  this  belongs  to  the  virtue  of  patience  or 
fortitude,  as  also  to  acknowledge  one's  own  infirmity,  and 
this  belongs  to  the  perfection  that  is  called  humility. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Sometimes  a  person  performs  the  exterior 
act  of  a  virtue  without  having  the  virtue,  and  from  some 
other  cause  than  virtue.  Hence  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iii.  8) 
mentions  five  ways  in  which  people  are  said  to  be  brave  by 
way  of  resemblance,  through  performing  acts  of  fortitude 
without  having  the  virtue.  This  may  be  done  in  three 
ways.  First,  because  they  tend  to  that  which  is  difficult 
as  though  it  were  not  difficult:  and  this  again  happens  in 
three  ways,  for  sometimes  this  is  owing  to  ignorance, 
through  not  perceiving  the  greatness  of  the  danger;  some- 
times it  is  owing  to  the  fact  that  one  is  hopeful  of  overcoming 
dangers— when,  for  instance,  one  has  often  experienced 
escape  from  danger ;  and  sometimes  this  is  owing  to  a  certain 
science  and  art,  as  in  the  case  of  soldiers  who,  through  skill 
and  practice  in  the  use  of  arms,  think  little  of  the  dangers 
of  battle,  as  they  reckon  themselves  capable  of  defending 
themselves  against  them;  thus  Vegetius  says  (De Re  Milit.  i.), 
No  man  fears  to  do  what  he  is  confident  of  having  learnt  to 
do  well.  Secondly,  a  man  performs  an  act  of  fortitude 
without  having  the  virtue,  through  the  impulse  of  a  passion, 


Q.  i23.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  196 

whether  of  sorrow  that  he  wishes  to  cast  off,  or  again  of 
anger.  Thirdly,  through  choice,  not  indeed  of  a  due  end, 
but  of  some  temporal  advantage  to  be  obtained,  such  as 
honour,  pleasure,  or  gain,  or  of  some  disadvantage  to  be 
avoided,  such  as  blame,  pain,  or  loss. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  fortitude  of  the  soul  which  is  reckoned 
a  virtue,  as  explained  in  the  Reply  to  the  First  Objection, 
is  so  called  from  its  likeness  to  fortitude  of  the  body.  Nor 
is  it  inconsistent  with  the  notion  of  virtue,  that  a  man 
should  have  a  natural  inclination  to  virtue  by  reason  of 
his  natural  temperament,  as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXIII., 
A.  1). 

Second  Article, 
whether  fortitude  is  a  special  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fortitude  is  not  a  special  virtue. 
For  it  is  written  (Wis.  viii.  7) :  She  teacheth  temperance, 
and  prudence,  and  justice,  and  fortitude,  where  the  text 
has  virtue  for  fortitude.  Since  then  the  term  virtue  is 
common  to  all  virtues,  it  seems  that  fortitude  is  a  general 
virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Ambrose  says  (De  Offic.  i) :  Fortitude  is 
not  lacking  in  courage,  for  alone  she  defends  the  honour  of  the 
virtues  and  guards  their  behests.  She  it  is  that  wages  an 
inexorable  war  on  all  vice,  undeterred  by  toil,  brave  in  face  of 
dangers,  steeled  against  pleasures,  unyielding  to  lusts,  avoiding 
covetousness  as  a  deformity  that  weakens  virtue;  and  he  says 
the  same  further  on  in  connexion  with  other  vices.  Now 
this  cannot  apply  to  any  special  virtue.  Therefore  fortitude 
is  not  a  special  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Fortitude  would  seem  to  derive  its  name 
from  firmness.  But  it  belongs  to  every  virtue  to  stand 
firm,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  ii.  Therefore  fortitude  is  a  general 
virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  {Moral,  xxii.)  numbers  it  among 
the  other  virtues. 


197  FORTITUDE  Q  123  Art.  2 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXI.,  AA.  3,  4), 
the  term  fortitude  can  be  taken  in  two  ways.  First,  as 
simply  denoting  a  certain  firmness  of  mind,  and  in  this  sense 
it  is  a  general  virtue,  or  rather  a  condition  of  every  virtue, 
since  as  the  Philosopher  states  {Ethic,  ii),  it  is  requisite 
for  every  virtue  to  act  firmly  and  immovably.  Secondly, 
fortitude  may  be  taken  to  denote  firmness  only  in  bearing 
and  withstanding  those  things  wherein  it  is  most  difficult 
to  be  firm,  namely  in  certain  grave  dangers.  Therefore 
Tully  says  (Rhet.  ii.),  that  fortitude  is  deliberate  facing  of 
dangers  and  bearing  of  toils.  In  this  sense  fortitude 
is  reckoned  a  special  virtue,  because  it  has  a  special 
matter. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  According  to  the  Philosopher  (De  Ccelo 
i.  116)  the  word  virtue  refers  to  the  extreme  limit  of  a  power. 
Now  a  natural  power  is,  in  one  sense,  the  power  of  resisting 
corruptions,  and  in  another  sense  is  a  principle  of  action, 
as  stated  in  Met.  v.  17.  And  since  this  latter  meaning  is 
the  more  common,  the  term  virtue,  as  denoting  the  extreme 
limit  of  such  a  power,  is  a  common  term,  for  virtue  taken  in  a 
general  sense  is  nothing  else  than  a  habit  whereby  one  acts 
well.  But  as  denoting  the  extreme  limit  of  power  in  the 
first  sense,  which  sense  is  more  specific,  it  is  applied  to  a 
special  virtue,  namely  fortitude,  to  which  it  belongs  to 
stand  firm  against  all  kinds  of  assaults. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Ambrose  takes  fortitude  in  a  broad  sense, 
as  denoting  firmness  of  mind  in  face  of  assaults  of  all  kinds. 
Nevertheless  even  as  a  special  virtue  with  a  determinate 
matter,  it  helps  to  resist  the  assaults  of  all  vices.  For  he 
that  can  stand  firm  in  things  that  are  most  difficult  to  bear, 
is  prepared,  in  consequence,  to  resist  those  which  are  less 
difficult. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  This  objection  takes  fortitude  in  the  first 
sense. 


Q.  i23.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  198 

Third  Article, 
whether  fortitude  is  about  fear  and  daring  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fortitude  is  not  about  fear  and 
daring.  For  Gregory  says  (Moral,  vii. ) :  The  fortitude  of  the 
just  man  is  to  overcome  the  flesh,  to  withstand  self-indulgence, 
to  quench  the  lusts  of  the  present  life.  Therefore  fortitude 
seems  to  be  about  pleasures  rather  than  about  fear  and 
daring. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Tully  says  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.),  that  it 
belongs  to  fortitude  to  face  dangers  and  to  bear  toil.  But 
this  seemingly  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  passions  of  fear  and 
daring,  but  rather  with  a  man's  toilsome  deeds  and  external 
dangers.     Therefore  fortitude  is  not  about  fear  and  daring. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Not  only  daring,  but  also  hope,  is  opposed 
to  fear,  as  stated  above  (I  .-II.,  Q.  XLV.,  A.  1,  ad  2)  in  the 
treatise  on  passions.  Therefore  fortitude  should  not  be 
about  daring  any  more  than  about  hope. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  ii.  7;  iii.  9) 
that  fortitude  is  about  fear  and  daring. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  1),  it  belongs  to  the 
virtue  of  fortitude  to  remove  any  obstacle  that  withdraws 
the  will  from  following  the  reason.  Now  to  be  withdrawn 
from  something  difficult  belongs  to  the  notion  of  fear, 
which  denotes  withdrawal  from  an  evil  that  entails  difficulty, 
as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  XLIL,  AA.  3,  5)  in  the  treatise  on 
passions.  Hence  fortitude  is  chiefly  about  fear  of  difficult 
thi  ngs,  which  can  withdraw  the  will  from  following  the  reason. 
And  it  behoves  one  not  only  firmly  to  bear  the  assault  of 
these  difficulties  by  restraining  fear,  but  also  moderately 
to  withstand  them,  when,  to  wit,  it  is  necessary  to  dispel 
them  altogether  in  order  to  free  oneself  therefrom  for  the 
future,  which  seems  to  come  under  the  notion  of  daring. 
Therefore  fortitude  is  about  fear  and  daring,  as  curbing 
fear  and  moderating  daring. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Gregory  is  speaking  then  of  the  fortitude 


199  FORTITUDE  Q.  123.  Art.  3 

of  the  just  man,  as  to  its  common  relation  to  all  virtues. 
Hence  he  first  of  all  mentions  matters  pertaining  to  tem- 
perance, as  in  the  words  quoted,  and  then  adds  that  which 
pertains  properly  to  fortitude  as  a  special  virtue,  by 
saying:  To  love  the  trials  of  this  life  for  the  sake  of  an  eternal 
reward. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Dangers  and  toils  do  not  withdraw  the 
will  from  the  course  of  reason,  except  in  so  far  as  they  are 
an  object  of  fear.  Hence  fortitude  needs  to  be  immediately 
about  fear  and  daring,  but  mediately  about  dangers  and  toils, 
these  being  the  objects  of  those  passions. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Hope  is  opposed  to  fear  on  the  part  of  the 
object,  for  hope  is  of  good,  fear  of  evil:  whereas  daring  is 
about  the  same  object,  and  is  opposed  to  fear  by  way  of 
approach  and  withdrawal,  as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  XLV., 
A.  1).  And  since  fortitude  properly  regards  those  temporal 
evils  that  withdraw  one  from  virtue,  as  appears  from  Tully's 
definition  quoted  in  the  Second  Objection,  it  follows  that 
fortitude  properly  is  about  fear  and  daring  and  not  about 
hope,  except  in  so  far  as  it  is  connected  with  daring,  as 
stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  XLV.,  A.  2). 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  fortitude  is  only  about  dangers  of 

DEATH  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fortitude  is  not  only  about 
dangers  of  death.  For  Augustine  says  (De  Morib.  Eccl.  xv.) 
that  fortitude  is  love  bearing  all  things  readily  for  the  sake 
of  the  object  beloved:  and  {Music,  vi.)  he  says  that  fortitude 
is  the  love  which  dreads  no  hardship,  not  even  death.  There- 
fore fortitude  is  not  only  about  danger  of  death,  but  also 
about  other  afflictions. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  All  the  passions  of  the  soul  need  to  be 
reduced  to  a  mean  by  some  virtue.  Now  there  is  no  other 
virtue  reducing  fears  to  a  mean.  Therefore  fortitude  is  not 
only  about  fear  of  death,  but  also  about  other  fears. 


Q.  123.  Art  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  200 

Obj.  3.  Further,  No  virtue  is  about  extremes.  But  fear 
of  death  is  about  an  extreme,  since  it  is  the  greatest  of  fears, 
as  stated  in  Ethic,  hi.  Therefore  the  virtue  of  fortitude  is 
not  about  fear  of  death. 

On  the  contrary,  Andronicus  says  that  fortitude  is  a  virtue 
of  the  irascible  faculty  that  is  not  easily  deterred  by  the  fear  of 
death. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  3),  it  belongs  to  the 
virtue  of  fortitude  to  guard  the  will  against  being  withdrawn 
from  the  good  of  reason  through  fear  of  bodily  evil.  Now 
it  behoves  one  to  hold  firmly  the  good  of  reason  against 
every  evil  whatsoever,  since  no  bodily  good  is  equivalent 
to  the  good  of  the  reason.  Hence  fortitude  of  soul  must 
be  that  which  binds  the  will  firmly  to  the  good  of  reason 
in  face  of  the  greatest  evils:  because  he  that  stands  firm 
against  great  things,  will  in  consequence  stand  firm  against 
less  things,  but  not  conversely.  Moreover  it  belongs  to 
the  notion  of  virtue  that  it  should  regard  something  extreme : 
and  the  most  fearful  of  all  bodily  evils  is  death,  since  it  does 
away  all  bodily  goods.  Wherefore  Augustine  says  (De 
Morib.  Eccl.  xxii.)  that  the  soul  is  shaken  by  its  fellow  body, 
with  fear  of  toil  and  pain,  lest  the  body  be  stricken  and  harassed 
with  fear  of  death  lest  it  be  done  away  and  destroyed.  There- 
fore the  virtue  of  fortitude  is  about  the  fear  of  dangers  of 
death. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Fortitude  behaves  well  in  bearing  all  manner 
of  adversity:  yet  a  man  is  not  reckoned  brave  simply 
through  bearing  any  kind  of  adversity,  but  only  through 
bearing  well  even  the  greatest  evils ;  while  through  bearing 
others  he  is  said  to  be  brave  in  a  restricted  sense. 

Reply  Obj.  a.  Since  fear  is  born  of  love,  any  virtue 
that  moderates  the  love  of  certain  goods  must  in  consequence 
moderate  the  fear  of  contrary  evils:  thus  liberality,  which 
moderates  the  love  of  money,  as  a  consequence,  moderates 
the  fear  of  losing  it,  and  the  same  is  the  case  with  tem- 
perance and  other  virtues.  But  to  love  one's  own  life  is 
natural :  and  hence  the  necessity  of  a  special  virtue  modifying 
the  fear  of  death. 


201  FORTITUDE  Q.  123.  Art.  5 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  virtues  the  extreme  consists  in  exceeding 
right  reason:  wherefore  to  undergo  the  greatest  dangers  in 
accordance  with  reason  is  not  contrary  to  virtue. 


Fifth  Article. 

whether  fortitude  is  properly  about  dangers 
of  death  in  battle  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fortitude  is  not  properly  about 
dangers  of  death  in  battle.  For  martyrs  above  all  are 
commended  for  their  fortitude.  But  martyrs  are  not  com- 
mended in  connexion  with .  battle.  Therefore  fortitude  is 
not  properly  about  dangers  of  death  in  battle. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Ambrose  says  (De  Offic.  i.)  that  fortitude 
is  applicable  both  to  warlike  and  to  civil  matters :  and  Tully 
(De  Offic.  i.),  under  the  heading,  '  That  it  pertains  to  forti- 
tude to  excel  in  battle  rather  than  in  civil  life,'  says: 
Although  not  a  few  think  that  the  business  of  war  is  of  greater 
importance  than  the  affairs  of  civil  life,  this  opinion  must  be 
qualified:  and  if  we  wish  to  judge  the  matter  truly,  there  are 
many  things  in  civil  life  that  are  more  important  and  more 
glorious  than  those  connected  with  war.  Now  greater  forti- 
tude is  about  greater  things.  Therefore  fortitude  is  not 
properly  concerned  with  death  in  battle. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  War  is  directed  to  the  preservation  of 
a  country's  temporal  peace:  for  Augustine  says  (De  Civ. 
Dei  xix.)  that  wars  are  waged  in  order  to  insure  peace. 
Now  it  does  not  seem  that  one  ought  to  expose  oneself  to 
the  danger  of  death  for  the  temporal  peace  of  one's  country, 
since  this  same  peace  is  the  occasion  of  much  licence  in 
morals.  Therefore  it  seems  that  the  virtue  of  fortitude 
is  not  about  the  danger  of  death  in  battle. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.)  that 
fortitude  is  chiefly  about  death  in  battle. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  4),  fortitude  streng- 
thens a  man's  mind  against  the  greatest  danger,  which  is 
that  of  death.     Now  fortitude  is  a  virtue ;  and  it  is  essential 


Q.i23.Art.5     THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  202 

to  virtue  ever  to  tend  to  good;  wherefore  it  is  in  order  to 
pursue  some  good  that  man  does  not  fly  from  the  danger 
of  death.  But  the  dangers  of  death  arising  out  of  sickness, 
storms  at  sea,  attacks  from  robbers,  and  the  like,  do  not 
seem  to  come  on  a  man  through  his  pursuing  some  good. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  dangers  of  death  which  occur  in 
battle  come  to  man  directly  on  account  of  some  good, 
because,  to  wit,  he  is  defending  the  common  good  by  a  just 
fight.  Now  a  just  fight  is  of  two  kinds.  First,  there  is 
the  general  combat,  for  instance,  of  those  who  fight  in  battle ; 
secondly,  there  is  the  private  combat,  as  when  a  judge  or 
even  private  individual  does  not  refrain  from  giving  a  just 
judgement  through  fear  of  the  impending  sword,  or  any 
other  danger  though  it  threaten  death.  Hence  it  belongs 
to  fortitude  to  strengthen  the  mind  against  dangers  of  death, 
not  only  such  as  arise  in  a  general  battle,  but  also  such  as 
occur  in  singular  combat,  which  may  be  called  by  the 
general  name  of  battle.  Accordingly  it  must  be  granted 
that  fortitude  is  properly  about  dangers  of  death  occurring 
in  battle. 

Moreover,  a  brave  man  behaves  well  in  face  of  danger 
of  any  other  kind  of  death ;  especially  since  man  may  be  in 
danger  of  any  kind  of  death  on  account  of  virtue:  thus 
may  a  man  not  fail  to  attend  on  a  sick  friend  through  fear 
of  deadly  infection,  or  not  refuse  to  undertake  a  journey 
with  some  godly  object  in  view  through  fear  of  shipwreck 
or  robbers. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Martyrs  face  the  fight  that  is  waged  against 
their  own  person,  and  this  for  the  sake  of  the  sovereign 
good  which  is  God ;  wherefore  their  fortitude  is  praised  above 
all.  Nor  is  it  outside  the  genus  of  fortitude  that  regards 
warlike  actions,  for  which  reason  they  are  said  to  have  been 
valiant  in  battle.* 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Personal  and  civil  business  is  differentiated 
from  the  business  of  war  that  regards  general  wars.     How- 
ever, personal  and  civil  affairs  admit  of  dangers  of  death 
arising  out  of  certain  conflicts  which  are  private  wars,  and 
*  Office  of  Martyrs,  ex.  Heb.  xi.  34. 


203  FORTITUDE  Q.  123.  Art.  6 

so  with  regard  to  these  also  there  may  be  fortitude  properly 
so  called. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  peace  of  the  state  is  good  in  itself,  nor 
does  it  become  evil  because  certain  persons  make  evil  use  of 
it.  For  there  are  many  others  who  make  good  use  of  it ;  and 
many  evils  prevented  by  it,  such  as  murders  and  sacrileges, 
are  much  greater  than  those  which  are  occasioned  by  it, 
and  which  belong  chiefly  to  the  sins  of  the  flesh. 


Sixth  Article. 

whether  endurance  is  the  chief  act  of 
fortitude  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  endurance  is  not  the  chief  act 
of  fortitude.  For  virtue  is  about  the  difficult  and  the  good 
(Ethic,  ii.  3).  Now  it  is  more  difficult  to  attack  than  to 
endure.  Therefore  endurance  is  not  the  chief  act  of  forti- 
tude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  To  be  able  to  act  on  another  seems  to 
argue  greater  power  than  not  to  be  changed  by  another. 
Now  to  attack  is  to  act  on  another,  and  to  endure  is  to 
persevere  unchangeably.  Since  then  fortitude  denotes 
perfection  of  power,  it  seems  that  it  belongs  to  fortitude 
to  attack  rather  than  to  endure. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  One  contrary  is  more  distant  from  the 
other  than  its  mere  negation.  Now  to  endure  is  merely 
not  to  fear,  whereas  to  attack  denotes  a  movement  contrary 
to  that  of  fear,  since  it  implies  pursuit.  Since  then  fortitude 
above  all  withdraws  the  mind  from  fear,  it  seems  that  it 
regards  attack  rather  than  endurance. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.  9)  that 
certain  persons  are  said  to  be  brave  chiefly  because  they 
endure  affliction. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  3),  and  according  to  the 
Philosopher  (Ethic,  iii.  9),  fortitude  is  more  concerned  to 
allay  fear,  than  to  moderate  daring.  For  it  is  more  difficult 
to  allay  fear  than  to  moderate  daring,  since  the  danger 


Q.i23.Art.6    THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  204 

which  is  the  object  of  daring  and  fear,  tends  by  its  very 
nature  to  check  daring,  but  to  increase  fear.  Now  to  attack 
belongs  to  fortitude  in  so  far  as  the  latter  moderates  daring- 
whereas  to  endure  follows  the  repression  of  fear.  Therefore 
the  principal  act  of  fortitude  is  endurance,  that  is  to  stand 
immovable  in  the  midst  of  dangers  rather  than  to  attack  them. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Endurance  is  more  difficult  than  aggression, 
for  three  reasons.  First,  because  endurance  seemingly 
implies  that  one  is  being  attacked  by  a  stronger  person, 
whereas  aggression  denotes  that  one  is  attacking  as  though 
one  were  the  stronger  party ;  and  it  is  more  difficult  to  con- 
tend with  a  stronger  than  with  a  weaker.  Secondly,  because 
he  that  endures  already  feels  the  presence  of  danger,  whereas 
the  aggressor  looks  upon  danger  as  something  to  come; 
and  it  is  more  difficult  to  be  unmoved  by  the  present  than 
by  the  future.  Thirdly,  because  endurance  implies  length 
of  time,  whereas  aggression  is  consistent  with  sudden 
movements;  and  it  is  more  difficult  to  remain  unmoved  for 
a  long  time,  than  to  be  moved  suddenly  to  something 
arduous.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.  8.)  that 
some  hurry  to  meet  danger,  yet  fly  when  the  danger  is  present; 
this  is  not  the  behaviour  of  a  brave  man. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Endurance  denotes  indeed  a  passion  of  the 
body,  but  an  action  of  the  soul  cleaving  most  resolutely 
(fortissime)  to  good,  the  result  being  that  it  does  not  yield 
to  the  threatening  passion  of  the  body.  Now  virtue  con- 
cerns the  soul  rather  than  the  body. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  He  that  endures  fears  not,  though  he  is 
confronted  with  the  cause  of  fear,  whereas  this  cause  is  not 
present  to  the  aggressor. 

Seventh  Article. 

whether  the  brave  man  acts  for  the  sake  of 
the  good  of  his  habit  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 
Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  brave  man  does  not  act 
for  the  sake  of  the  good  of  his  habit.     For  in  matters  of 


205  FORTITUDE  Q.  123.  Art.  7 

action  the  end,  though  first  in  intention,  is  last  in  execution. 
Now  the  act  of  fortitude,  in  the  order  of  execution,  follows 
the  habit  of  fortitude.  Therefore  it  is  impossible  for 
the  brave  man  to  act  for  the  sake  of  the  good  of  his 
habit. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  xiii.) :  We 
love  virtues  for  the  sake  of  happiness,  and  yet  some  make  bold 
to  counsel  us  to  be  virtuous,  namely  by  saying  that  we  should 
desire  virtue  for  its  own  sake,  without  loving  happiness.  If 
they  succeed  in  their  endeavour,  we  shall  surely  cease  to  love 
virtue  itself,  since  we  shall  no  longer  love  that  for  the  sake 
of  which  alone  we  love  virtue.  But  fortitude  is  a  virtue. 
Therefore  the  act  of  fortitude  is  directed  not  to  fortitude 
but  to  happiness. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  (De  Morib.  Eccl.  xv.) 
that  fortitude  is  love  ready  to  bear  all  things  for  God's  sake. 
Now  God  is  not  the  habit  of  fortitude,  but  something  better, 
since  the  end  must  needs  be  better  than  what  is  directed 
to  the  end.  Therefore  the  brave  man  does  not  act  for  the 
sake  of  the  good  of  his  habit. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.  7)  that 
to  the  brave  man  fortitude  itself  is  a  good:  and  such  is  an  end. 

/  answer  that,  An  end  is  twofold :  proximate  and  ultimate. 
Now  the  proximate  end  of  every  agent  is  to  introduce  a 
likeness  of  that  agent's  form  into  something  else:  thus  the 
end  of  fire  in  heating  is  to  introduce  the  likeness  of  its  heat 
into  some  passive  matter:  and  the  end  of  the  builder  is  to 
introduce  into  matter  the  likeness  of  his  art.  Whatever 
good  ensues  from  this,  if  it  be  intended,  may  be  called  the 
remote  end  of  the  agent.  Now  just  as  in  things  made 
external  matter  is  fashioned  by  art,  so  in  things  done, 
human  deeds  are  fashioned  by  prudence.  Accordingly 
we  must  conclude  that  the  brave  man  intends  as  his  proxi- 
mate end  to  reproduce  in  action  a  likeness  of  his  habit,  for 
he  intends  to  act  in  accordance  with  his  habit:  but  his 
remote  end  is  happiness  or  God. 

This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Objections :  for  the 
First  Objection  proceeds  as  though  the  very  essence  of  a 


Q.  123.  Art.  8     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  206 

habit  were  its  end,  instead  of  the  likeness  of  the  habit  in 
act,  as  stated.  The  other  two  objections  consider  the 
ultimate  end. 

Eighth  Article, 
whether  the  brave  man  delights  in  his  act  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  brave  man  delights  in  his 
act.  For  delight  is  the  unhindered  action  of  a  connatural 
habit  (Ethic,  x.  4,  6,  8).  Now  the  brave  deed  proceeds  from 
a  habit  which  acts  after  the  manner  of  nature.  Therefore 
the  brave  man  takes  pleasure  in  his  act. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Ambrose,  commenting  on  Gal.  v.  22, 
But  the  fruit  of  the  Spirit  is  charity,  joy,  peace,  says  that 
deeds  of  virtue  are  called  fruits  because  they  refresh  man's 
mind  with  a  holy  and  pure  delight.  Now  the  brave  man  per- 
forms acts  of  virtue.     Therefore  he  takes  pleasure  in  his  act. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  weaker  is  overcome  by  the  stronger. 
Now  the  brave  man  has  a  stronger  love  for  the  good  of  virtue 
than  for  his  own  body,  which  he  exposes  to  the  danger  of 
death.  Therefore  the  delight  in  the  good  of  virtue  banishes 
the  pain  of  the  body;  and  consequently  the  brave  man 
does  all  things  with  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.  9)  that 
the  brave  man  seems  to  have  no  delight  in  his  act. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  XXXI.,  AA.  3, 4, 5) 
where  we  were  treating  of  the  passions,  pleasure  is  two- 
fold; one  is  bodily,  resulting  from  bodily  contact,  the  other 
is  spiritual,  resulting  from  an  apprehension  of  the  soul. 
It  is  the  latter  which  properly  results  from  deeds  of  virtue, 
since  in  them  we  consider  the  good  of  reason.  Now  the 
principal  act  of  fortitude  is  to  endure,  not  only  certain 
things  that  are  unpleasant  as  apprehended  by  the  soul — for 
instance,  the  loss  of  bodily  life,  which  the  virtuous  man 
loves  not  only  as  a  natural  good,  but  also  as  being  necessary 
for  acts  of  virtue,  and  things  connected  with  them — but  also 
to  endure  things  unpleasant  in  respect  of  bodily  contact, 
such  as  wounds  and  blows.     Hence  the  brave  man,  on  one 


207  FORTITUDE  Q.  123.  Art.  8 

side,  has  something  that  affords  him  delight,  namely  as 
regards  spiritual  pleasure,  in  the  act  itself  of  virtue  and 
the  end  thereof :  while,  on  the  other  hand,  he  has  cause  for 
both  spiritual  sorrow,  in  the  thought  of  losing  his  life,  and 
for  bodily  pain.  Hence  we  read  (2  Machab.  vi.  30)  that 
Eleazar  said :  /  suffer  grievous  pains  in  body:  but  in  soul  am 
well  content  to  suffer  these  things  because  I  fear  Thee. 

Now  the  sensible  pain  of  the  body  makes  one  insensible 
to  the  spiritual  delight  of  virtue,  without  the  copious 
assistance  of  God's  grace,  which  has  more  strength  to  raise 
the  soul  to  the  Divine  things  in  which  it  delights,  than 
bodily  pains  have  to  afflict  it.  Thus  the  Blessed  Tiburtius, 
while  walking  barefoot  on  the  burning  coal,  said  that 
he  felt  as  though  he  were  walking  on  roses. 

Yet  the  virtue  of  fortitude  prevents  the  reason  from 
being  entirely  overcome  by  bodily  pain.  And  the  delight 
of  virtue  overcomes  spiritual  sorrow,  inasmuch  as  a  man 
prefers  the  good  of  virtue  to  the  life  of  the  body  and  to 
whatever  appertains  thereto.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic,  ii.  3 ;  iii.  9)  that  it  is  not  necessary  for  a  brave  man  to 
delight  so  as  to  perceive  his  delight,  but  it  suffices  for  him  not 
to  be  sad. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  vehemence  of  the  action  or  passion  of 
one  power  hinders  the  action  of  another  power:  wherefore 
the  pain  in  his  senses  hinders  the  mind  of  the  brave  man 
from  feeling  delight  in  its  proper  operation. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Deeds  of  virtue  are  delightful  chiefly  on 
account  of  their  end;  yet  they  can  be  painful  by  their 
nature,  and  this  is  principally  the  case  with  fortitude. 
Hence  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.  9)  that  to  perform 
deeds  with  pleasure  does  not  happen  in  all  virtues,  except  in 
so  far  as  one  attains  the  end. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  the  brave  man  spiritual  sorrow  is  over- 
come by  the  delight  of  virtue.  Yet  since  bodily  pain  is 
more  sensible,  and  the  sensitive  apprehension  is  more  in 
evidence  to  man,  it  follows  that  spiritual  pleasure  in  the 
end  of  virtue  fades  away,  so  to  speak,  in  the  presence  of 
great  bodily  pain, 


Q.  123.  Art.  9     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  208 


Ninth  Article. 

whether  fortitude  deals  chiefly  with  sudden 

occurrences  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Ninth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fortitude  does  not  deal  chiefly 
with  sudden  occurrences.  For  it  would  seem  that  things 
occur  suddenly  when  they  are  unforeseen.  But  Tully  says 
(De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  fortitude  is  the  deliberate  facing  of 
danger,  and  bearing  of  toil.  Therefore  fortitude  does  not 
deal  chiefly  with  sudden  happenings. 

Ob].  2.  Further,  Ambrose  says  {De  Offic.  i.):  The  brave 
man  is  not  unmindful  of  what  may  be  likely  to  happen;  he 
takes  measures  beforehand,  and  looks  out  as  from  the  conning- 
tower  of  his  mind,  so  as  to  encounter  the  future  by  his  fore- 
thought, lest  he  should  say  afterwards:  This  befel  me  because  I 
did  not  think  it  could  possibly  happen.  But  it  is  not  possible 
to  be  prepared  for  the  future  in  the  case  of  sudden  occurrences. 
Therefore  the  operation  of  fortitude  is  not  concerned  with 
sudden  happenings. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.  8)  that 
the  brave  man  is  of  good  hope.  But  hope  looks  forward  to  the 
future,  which  is  inconsistent  with  sudden  occurrences. 
Therefore  the  operation  of  fortitude  is  not  concerned  with 
sudden  happenings. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.  8)  that 
fortitude  is  chiefly  about  sudden  dangers  of  death. 

I  answer  that,  Two  things  must  be  considered  in  the 
operation  of  fortitude.  One  is  in  regard  to  its  choice :  and 
thus  fortitude  is  not  about  sudden  occurrences :  because  the 
brave  man  chooses  to  think  beforehand  of  the  dangers  that 
may  arise,  in  order  to  be  able  to  withstand  them,  or  to  bear 
them  more  easily:  since  according  to  Gregory  {Horn.  xxv. 
in  Ev.),  the  blow  that  is  foreseen  strikes  with  less  force,  and  we 
are  able  more  easily  to  bear  earthly  wrongs,  if  we  are  forearmed 
with  the  shield  of  foreknowledge.  The  other  thing  to  be  con- 
sidered in  the  operation  of  fortitude  regards  the  display  of  the 


209  FORTITUDE  Q.  123.  Art.  10 

virtuous  habit:  and  in  this  way  fortitude  is  chiefly  about 
sudden  occurrences,  because  according  to  the  Philosopher 
(Ethic,  iii.  8)  the  habit  of  fortitude  is  displayed  chiefly  in 
sudden  dangers:  since  a  habit  works  by  way  of  nature. 
Wherefore  if  a  person  without  forethought  does  that 
which  pertains  to  virtue,  when  necessity  urges  on  account 
of  some  sudden  ganger,  this  is  a  very  strong  proof  that 
habitual  fortitude  is  firmly  seated  in  his  mind. 

Yet  is  it  possible  for  a  person,  even  without  the  habit  of 
fortitude,  to  prepare  his  mind  against  danger  by  long  fore- 
thought :  in  the  same  way  as  a  brave  man  prepares  himself 
when  necessary.  This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Objec- 
tions. 

Tenth  Article. 

whether  the  brave  man  makes  use  of  anger  in 

his  action  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Tenth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  brave  man  does  not  use 
anger  in  his  action.  For  no  one  should  employ  as  an  instru- 
ment of  his  action  that  which  he  cannot  use  at  will.  Now 
man  cannot  use  anger  at  will,  so  as  to  take  it  up  and  lay 
it  aside  when  he  will.  For,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (De 
Memoria  ii.),  when  a  bodily  passion  is  in  movement,  it  does 
not  rest  at  once  just  as  one  wishes.  Therefore  a  brave  man 
should  not  employ  anger  for  his  action. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  If  a  man  is  competent  to  do  a  thing  by 
himself,  he  should  not  seek  the  assistance  of  something 
weaker  and  more  imperfect.  Now  the  reason  is  competent 
to  achieve  by  itself  deeds  of  fortitude,  wherein  anger  is 
impotent:  wherefore  Seneca  says  (De  Ira  i.) :  Reason  by 
itself  suffices  not  only  to  make  us  prepared  for  action  but  also 
to  accomplish  it.  In  fact  is  there  greater  folly  than  for  reason 
to  seek  help  from  anger  P  the  steadfast  from  the  unstaid,  the 
trusty  from  the  untrustworthy ,  the  healthy  from  the  sick  ? 
Therefore  a  brave  man  should  not  make  use  of  anger. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Just  as  people  are  more  earnest  in  doing 
deeds  of  fortitude  on  account  of  anger,  so  are  they  on  account 

11.  ii.  4  14 


Q.  123.  Art.  10     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  210 

of  sorrow  or  desire;  wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic. 
iii.  8)  that  wild  beasts  are  incited  to  face  danger  through 
sorrow  or  pain,  and  adulterous  persons  dare  many  things  for 
the  sake  of  desire.  Now  fortitude  employs  neither  sorrow 
nor  desire  for  its  action.  Therefore  in  like  manner  it  should 
not  employ  anger. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.  loc.  cit.) 
that  anger  helps  the  brave. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  XXIV.,  A.  2), 
concerning  anger  and  the  other  passions  there  was  a  difference 
of  opinion  between  the  Peripatetics  and  the  Stoics.  For  the 
Stoics  excluded  anger  and  all  other  passions  of  the  soul  from 
the  mind  of  a  wise  or  good  man :  whereas  the  Peripatetics, 
of  whom  Aristotle  was  the  chief,  ascribed  to  virtuous  men 
both  anger  and  the  other  passions  of  the  soul  albeit  modified 
by  reason.  And  possibly  they  differed  not  in  reality  but  in 
their  way  of  speaking.  For  the  Peripatetics,  as  stated  above 
{loc.  cit.),  gave  the  name  of  passions  to  all  the  movements 
of  the  sensitive  appetite,  however  they  may  comport  them- 
selves. And  since  the  sensitive  appetite  is  moved  by  the 
command  of  reason,  so  that  it  may  co-operate  by  rendering 
action  more  prompt,  they  held  that  virtuous  persons  should 
employ  both  anger  and  the  other  passions  of  the  soul, 
modified  according  to  the  dictate  of  reason.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  Stoics  gave  the  name  of  passions  to  certain  immo- 
derate emotions  of  the  sensitive  appetite,  wherefore  they 
called  them  sicknesses  or  diseases,  and  for  this  reason 
severed  them  altogether  from  virtue. 

Accordingly  the  brave  man  employs  moderate  anger  for 
his  action,  but  not  immoderate  anger. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Anger  that  is  moderated  in  accordance  with 
reason  is  subject  to  the  command  of  reason :  so  that  man  uses 
it  at  his  will,  which  would  not  be  the  case  were  it  immo- 
derate. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Reason  employs  anger  for  its  action,  not  as 
seeking  its  assistance,  but  because  it  uses  the  sensitive 
appetite  as  an  instrument,  just  as  it  uses  the  members  of 
the  body      Nor  is  it  unbecoming  for  the  instrument  to  be 


2ii  FORTITUDE  Q.  123.  Art.  10 

more  imperfect  than  the  principal  agent,  even  as  the  hammer 
is  more  imperfect  than  the  smith.  Moreover,  Seneca  was  a 
follower  of  the  Stoics,  and  the  above  words  were  aimed  by 
him  directly  at  Aristotle. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Whereas  fortitude,  as  stated  above  (A.  6), 
has  two  acts,  namely  endurance  and  aggression,  it  employs 
anger,  not  for  the  act  of  endurance,  because  the  reason  by 
itself  performs  this  act,  but  for  the  act  of  aggression,  for 
which  it  employs  anger  rather  than  the  other  passions, 
since  it  belongs  to  anger  to  strike  at  the  cause  of  sorrow, 
so  that  it  directly  co-operates  with  fortitude  in  attacking. 
On  the  other  hand,  sorrow  by  its  very  nature  gives  way  to 
the  thing  that  hurts ;  though  accidentally  it  helps  in  aggres- 
sion, either  as  being  the  cause  of  anger,  as  stated  above 
(I. -II. ,  Q.  XLVII. ,  A.  3),  or  as  making  a  person  expose  himself 
to  danger  in  order  to  escape  from  sorrow.  In  like  manner 
desire,  by  its  very  nature,  tends  to  a  pleasurable  good,  to 
which  it  is  directly  contrary  to  withstand  danger:  yet 
accidentally  sometimes  it  helps  one  to  attack,  in  so  far  as 
one  prefers  to  risk  dangers  rather  than  lack  pleasure.  Hence 
the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  hi.  5) :  Of  all  the  cases  in  which 
fortitude  arises  from  a  passion,  the  most  natural  is  when  a 
man  is  brave  through  anger,  making  his  choice  and  acting  for 
a  purpose,  i.e.  for  a  due  end;  this  is  true  fortitude . 

Eleventh  Article, 
whether  fortitude  is  a  cardinal  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eleventh  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fortitude  is  not  a  cardinal 
virtue.  For,  as  stated  above  (A.  10) ,  anger  is  closely  allied 
with  fortitude.  Now  anger  is  not  accounted  a  principal 
passion;  nor  is  daring  which  belongs  to  fortitude.  Therefore 
neither  should  fortitude  be  reckoned  a  cardinal  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  object  of  virtue  is  good.  But  the 
direct  object  of  fortitude  is  not  good,  but  evil,  for  it  is 
endurance  of  evil  and  toil,  as  Tully  says  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.). 
Therefore  fortitude  is  not  a  cardinal  virtue. 


Q.  123.  Art.  u     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  212 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  cardinal  virtues  are  about  those 
things  upon  which  human  life  is  chiefly  occupied,  just  as  a 
door  turns  upon  a  hinge  {car dine).  But  fortitude  is  about 
dangers  of  death  which  are  of  rare  occurrence  in  human 
life.  Therefore  fortitude  should  not  be  reckoned  a  cardinal 
or  principal  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  (Moral,  xxii.),  Ambrose  in  his 
commentary  on  Luke  vi.  20,  and  Augustine  (De  Moribus 
Eccl.  xv.),  number  fortitude  among  the  four  cardinal  or 
principal  virtues. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (I. -II.,  0.  LXL,  AA.  3,  4), 
those  virtues  are  said  to  be  cardinal  or  principal  which  have 
a  foremost  claim  to  that  which  belongs  to  the  virtues  in 
common.  And  among  other  conditions  of  virtue  in  general 
one  is  that  it  is  stated  to  act  steadfastly,  according  to  Ethic,  ii.  4. 
Now  fortitude  above  all  lays  claim  to  praise  for  steadfast- 
ness. Because  he  that  stands  firm  is  so  much  the  more 
praised,  as  he  is  more  strongly  impelled  to  fall  or  recede. 
Now  man  is  impelled  to  recede  from  that  which  is  in  accor- 
dance with  reason,  both  by  the  pleasing  good  and  the  dis- 
pleasing evil.  But  bodily  pain  impels  him  more  strongly 
than  pleasure.  For  Augustine  says  (QQ.  LXXXIII.,  qu.  36) : 
There  is  none  that  does  not  shun  pain  more  than  he  desires 
pleasure.  For  we  perceive  that  even  the  most  untamed  beasts 
are  deterred  from  the  greatest  pleasures  by  the  fear  of  pain. 
And  among  the  pains  of  the  mind  and  dangers  those  are 
mostly  feared  which  lead  to  death,  and  it  is  against  them 
that  the  brave  man  stands  firm.  Therefore  fortitude  is  a 
cardinal  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Daring  and  anger  do  not  co-operate  with 
fortitude  in  its  act  of  endurance,  wherein  its  steadfastness 
is  chiefly  commended:  for  it  is  by  that  act  that  the  brave 
man  curbs  fear,  which  is  a  principal  passion,  as  stated  above 
(I.-II.,Q.  XXV.,  A.  4). 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Virtue  is  directed  to  the  good  of  reason 
which  it  behoves  to  safeguard  against  the  onslaught  of 
evils.  And  fortitude  is  directed  to  evils  of  the  body,  as 
contraries  which  it  withstands,  and  to  the  good  of  reason, 
as  the  end,  which  it  intends  to  safeguard. 


213  FORTITUDE  Q.  123.  Art.  12 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Though  dangers  of  death  are  of  rare  occur- 
rence, yet  the  occasions  of  those  dangers  occur  frequently, 
since  on  account  of  justice  which  he  pursues,  and  also  on 
account  of  other  good  deeds,  man  encounters  mortal  adver- 
saries. 

Twelfth  Article, 
whether  fortitude  excels  among  all  other 

VIRTUES  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Twelfth  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fortitude  excels  among  all  other 
virtues.  For  Ambrose  says  (De  Offtc.  i) :  Fortitude  is  higher, 
so  to  speak,  than  the  rest. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Virtue  is  about  that  which  is  difficult 
and  good.  But  fortitude  is  about  most  difficult  things. 
Therefore  it  is  the  greatest  of  the  virtues. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  person  of  a  man  is  more  excellent 
than  his  possessions.  But  fortitude  is  about  a  man's 
person,  for  it  is  this  that  a  man  exposes  to  the  danger  of 
death  for  the  good  of  virtue:  whereas  justice  and  the  other 
moral  virtues  are  about  other  and  external  things.  There- 
fore fortitude  is  the  chief  of  the  moral  virtues. 

Obj.  4.  On  the  contrary,  Tully  says  (DeOjfic.  i.):  Justice  is 
the  most  resplendent  of  the  virtues  and  gives  its  name  to  a  good 
man. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  (Rhet.  i.  19):  Those 
virtues  must  needs  be  greatest  which  are  most  profitable  to 
others.  Now  liberality  seems  to  be  more  useful  than  forti- 
tude.    Therefore  it  is  a  greater  virtue. 

I  answer  that,  As  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  vi.),  In  things 
that  are  great,  but  not  in  bulk,  to  be  great  is  to  be  good:  wherefore 
the  better  a  virtue  the  greater  it  is.  Now  reason's  good  is 
man's  good,  according  to  Dionysius  (Div.  Nom.  iv.)  Prudence, 
since  it  is  a  perfection  of  reason,  has  the  good  essentially: 
while  justice  effects  this  good,  since  it  belongs  to  justice 
to  establish  the  order  of  reason  in  all  human  affairs :  whereas 
the  other  virtues  safeguard  this  good,  inasmuch  as  they 
moderate   the   passions,    lest   they   lead   man   away   from 


Q.  123.  Art.  12    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  214 

reason's  good.  As  to  the  order  of  the  latter,  fortitude 
holds  the  first  place,  because  fear  of  dangers  of  death  has  the 
greatest  power  to  make  man  recede  from  the  good  of  reason : 
and  after  fortitude  comes  temperance,  since  also  pleasures 
of  touch  excel  all  others  in  hindering  the  good  of  reason. 
Now  to  be  a  thing  essentially  ranks  before  effecting  it,  and 
the  latter  ranks  before  safeguarding  it  by  removing  obstacles 
thereto.  Wherefore  among  the  cardinal  virtues,  prudence 
ranks  first,  justice  second,  fortitude  third,  temperance 
fourth,  and  after  these  the  other  virtues. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Ambrose  places  fortitude  before  the  other 
virtues,  in  respect  of  a  certain  general  utility,  inasmuch 
as  it  is  useful  both  in  warfare,  and  in  matters  relating  to 
civil  or  home  life.  Hence  he  begins  by  saying  (ibid.): 
Now  we  come  to  treat  of  fortitude,  which  being  higher  so  to 
speak  than  the  others,  is  applicable  both  to  warlike  and  to  civil 
matters. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Virtue  essentially  regards  the  good  rather 
than  the  difficult.  Hence  the  greatness  of  a  virtue  is 
measured  according  to  its  goodness  rather  than  its  difficulty. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  A  man  does  not  expose  his  person  to  dangers 
of  death  except  in  order  to  safeguard  justice:  wherefore 
the  praise  awarded  to  fortitude  depends  somewhat  on 
justice.  Hence  Ambrose  says  (De  Offic.  i.)  that  fortitude 
without  justice  is  an  occasion  of  injustice ;  since  the  stronger 
a  man  is  the  more  ready  is  he  to  oppress  the  weaker. 

The  Fourth  argument  is  granted. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  Liberality  is  useful  in  conferring  certain 
particular  favours :  whereas  a  certain  general  utility  attaches 
to  fortitude,  since  it  safeguards  the  whole  order  of  justice. 
Hence  the  Philosopher  says  (Rhet.  i.  9)  that  just  and  brave 
men  are  most  beloved,  because  they  are  most  useful  in  war  and 
peace. 


QUESTION  CXXIV. 

OF  MARTYRDOM. 
(In  Five  Articles). 

We  must  now  consider  martyrdom,  under  which  head  there 
are  rive  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  martyrdom  is  an  act 
of  virtue  ?  (2)  Of  what  virtue  is  it  the  act  ?  (3)  Concerning 
the  perfection  of  this  act:  (4)  The  pain  of  martyrdom: 
(5)  Its  cause. 

First  Article, 
whether  martyrdom  is  an  act  of  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  martyrdom  is  not  an  act  of 
virtue.  For  all  acts  of  virtue  are  voluntary.  But  martyr- 
dom is  sometimes  not  voluntary,  as  in  the  case  of  the 
Innocents  who  were  slain  for  Christ's  sake,  and  of  whom 
Hilary  says  (Super  Matth.  i.)  that  they  attained  the  ripe  age 
of  eternity  through  the  glory  of  martyrdom.  Therefore 
martyrdom  is  not  an  act  of  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Nothing  unlawful  is  an  act  of  virtue. 
Now  it  is  unlawful  to  kill  oneself,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXIV., 
A.  5),  and  yet  martyrdom  is  achieved  by  so  doing:  for 
Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  i.)  that  during  persecution 
certain  holy  women,  in  order  to  escape  from  those  who  threatened 
their  chastity,  threw  themselves  into  a  river,  and  so  ended  their 
lives,  and  their  martyrdom  is  honoured  in  the  Catholic  Church 
with  most  solemn  veneration.  Therefore  martyrdom  is  not 
an  act  of  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  is  praiseworthy  to  offer  oneself  to  do 
an  act   of  virtue.     But   it   is  not   praiseworthy  to  court 

215 


Q.  124.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  216 

martyrdom,  rather  would  it  seem  to  be  presumptuous  and 
rash.     Therefore  martyrdom  is  not  an  act  of  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  The  reward  of  beatitude  is  not  due  save 
to  acts  of  virtue.  Now  it  is  due  to  martyrdom,  since  it 
is  written  (Matth.  v.  10) :  Blessed  are  they  that  suffer  persecu- 
tion for  justice  sake,  for  theirs  is  the  kingdom  of  heaven. 
Therefore  martyrdom  is  an  act  of  virtue. 

J  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIIL.  AA.  1,  3), 
it  belongs  to  virtue  to  safeguard  man  in  the  good  of  reason. 
Now  the  good  of  reason  consists  in  the  truth  as  its  proper 
object,  and  in  justice  as  its  proper  effect,  as  shown  above 
(Q.  CIX.,  AA.  1,  2;  Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  12).  And  martyrdom 
consists  essentially  in  standing  firmly  to  truth  and  justice 
against  the  assaults  of  persecution.  Hence  it  is  evident 
that  martyrdom  is  an  act  of  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Some  have  said  that  in  the  case  of  the 
Innocents  the  use  of  their  free  will  was  miraculously  ac- 
celerated, so  that  they  suffered  martyrdom  even  voluntarily. 
Since,  however,  Scripture  contains  no  proof  of  this,  it  is 
better  to  say  that  these  babes  in  being  slain  obtained  by 
God's  grace  the  glory  of  martyrdom  which  others  acquire 
by  their  own  will.  For  the  shedding  of  one's  blood  for 
Christ's  sake  takes  the  place  of  Baptism.  Wherefore  just 
as  in  the  case  of  baptized  children  the  merit  of  Christ  is 
conducive  to  the  acquisition  of  glory  through  the  baptismal 
grace,  so  in  those  who  were  slain  for  Christ's  sake  the  merit 
of  Christ's  martyrdom  is  conducive  to  the  acquisition  of 
the  martyr's  palm.  Hence  Augustine  says  in  a  sermon 
on  the  Epiphany  (De  Diver  sis  lxvi.),  as  though  he  were 
addressing  them :  A  man  that  does  not  believe  that  children 
are  benefited  by  the  baptism  of  Christ  will  doubt  of  your  being 
crowned  in  suffering  for  Christ.  You  were  not  old  enough 
to  believe  in  Christ's  future  sufferings,  but  you  had  a  body 
wherein  you  could  endure  suffering  for  Christ  Who  was  to  suffer. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Augustine  says  (loc.  cit.)  that  possibly  the 
Church  was  induced  by  certain  credible  witnesses  of  Divine 
authority  thus  to  honour  the  memory  of  those  holy  women* 

*  Cf.  Q.  LXIV.,  A.  i,ad2. 


217  MARTYRDOM  Q.  124.  Art.  2 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  precepts  of  the  Law  are  about  acts  of 
virtue.  Now  it  has  been  stated  above  (Q.  CVIII. ,  A.  1,  ad  4) 
that  some  of  the  precepts  of  the  Divine  Law  are  to  be 
understood  in  reference  to  the  preparation  of  the  mind,  in 
the  sense  that  man  ought  to  be  prepared  to  do  such  and 
such  a  thing,  whenever  expedient.  In  the  same  way 
certain  things  belong  to  an  act  of  virtue  as  regards  the 
preparation  of  the  mind,  so  that  in  such  and  such  a  case  a 
man  should  act  according  to  reason.  And  this  observation 
would  seem  very  much  to  the  point  in  the  case  of  martyrdom, 
which  consists  in  the  right  endurance  of  sufferings  unjustly 
inflicted.  Nor  ought  a  man  to  give  another  an  occasion  of 
acting  unjustly:  yet  if  anyone  act  unjustly,  one  ought  to 
endure  it  in  moderation. 


Second  Article, 
whether  martyrdom  is  an  act  of  fortitude  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  martyrdom  is  not  an  act  of 
fortitude.  For  the  Greek  /xdprvp  signifies  a  witness.  Now 
witness  is  borne  to  the  faith  of  Christ,  according  to  Acts  i.  8, 
You  shall  be  witnesses  unto  Me,  etc.,  and  Maximus  says  in  a 
sermon:  The  mother  of  martyrs  is  the  Catholic  faith  which 
those  glorious  warriors  have  sealed  with  their  blood.  Therefore 
martyrdom  is  an  act  of  faith  rather  than  of  fortitude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  A  praiseworthy  act  belongs  chiefly  to  the 
virtue  which  inclines  thereto,  is  manifested  thereby,  and 
without  which  the  act  avails  nothing.  Now  charity  is  the 
chief  incentive  to  martyrdom:  Thus  Maximus  says  in  a 
sermon:  The  charity  of  Christ  is  victorious  in  His  martyrs. 
Again  the  greatest  proof  of  charity  lies  in  the  act  of  martyr- 
dom, according  to  John  xv.  13,  Greater  love  than  this  no  man 
hath,  that  a  man  lay  down  his  life  for  his  friends.  Moreover 
without  charity  martyrdom  avails  nothing,  according  to 
1  Cor.  xiii.  3,  //  /  should  deliver  my  body  to  be  burned,  and 
have  not  charity,  it  profiteth  me  nothing.  Therefore  martyr- 
dom is  an  act  of  charity  rather  than  of  fortitude. 


Q.  124.  Art,  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  218 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  in  a  sermon  on  S.  Cyprian: 
It  is  easy  to  honour  a  martyr  by  singing  his  praises,  but  it  is  a 
great  thing  to  imitate  his  faith  and  patience.  Now  that  which 
calls  chiefly  for  praise  in  a  virtuous  act,  is  the  virtue  of  which 
it  is  the  act.  Therefore  martyrdom  is  an  act  of  patience 
rather  than  of  fortitude. 

On  the  contrary,  Cyprian  says  (Ep.  ad  Mart,  et  Conf.  ii.): 
Blessed  martyrs,  with  what  praise  shall  I  extol  you  ?  Most 
valiant  warriors,  how  shall  I  find  words  to  proclaim  the  strength 
of  your  courage  ?  Now  a  person  is  praised  on  account  of 
the  virtue  whose  act  he  performs.  Therefore  martyrdom 
is  an  act  of  fortitude. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  1,  seq.), 
it  belongs  to  fortitude  to  strengthen  man  in  the  good  of 
virtue,  especially  against  dangers,  and  chiefly  against  dangers 
of  death,  and  most  of  all  against  those  that  occur  in  battle. 
Now  it  is  evident  that  in  martyrdom  man  is  firmly  strength- 
ened in  the  good  of  virtue,  since  he  cleaves  to  faith  and  justice 
notwithstanding  the  threatening  danger  of  death,  the 
imminence  of  which  is  moreover  due  to  a  kind  of  particular 
contest  with  his  persecutors.  Hence  Cyprian  says  in  a 
sermon  (loc.  cit.):  The  crowd  of  onlookers  wondered  to  see  an 
unearthly  battle,  and  Christ's  servants  fighting  erect,  undaunted 
in  speech,  with  souls  unmoved,  and  strength  divine.  Wherefore 
it  is  evident  that  martyrdom  is  an  act  of  fortitude ;  for  which 
reason  the  Church  reads  in  the  office  of  Martyrs  :  They 
became  valiant  in  battle.  * 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Two  things  must  be  considered  in  the  act  of 
fortitude.  One  is  the  good  wherein  the  brave  man  is 
strengthened,  and  this  is  the  end  of  fortitude ;  the  other  is 
the  firmness  itself,  whereby  a  man  does  not  yield  to  the 
contraries  that  hinder  him  from  achieving  that  good,  and  in 
this  consists  the  essence  of  fortitude.  Now  just  as  civic 
fortitude  strengthens  a  man's  mind  in  human  justice,  for 
the  safeguarding  of  which  he  braves  the  danger  of  death, 
so  gratuitous  fortitude  strengthens  man's  soul  in  the  good 

*  Heb.  xi.  34. 


219  MARTYRDOM  Q.  124,  Art.  3 

of  Divine  justice,  which  is  through  faith  in  Christ  Jesus, 
according  to  Rom.  hi.  22.  Thus  martyrdom  is  related  to 
faith  as  the  end  in  which  one  is  strengthened,  but  to  fortitude 
as  the  eliciting  habit. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Charity  inclines  one  to  the  act  of  martyrdom, 
as  its  first  and  chief  motive  cause,  being  the  virtue  com- 
manding it,  whereas  fortitude  inclines  thereto  as  being 
its  proper  motive  cause,  being  the  virtue  that  elicits  it. 
Hence  martyrdom  is  an  act  of  charity  as  commanding,  and 
of  fortitude  as  eliciting.  For  this  reason  also  it  manifests 
both  virtues.  It  is  due  to  charity  that  it  is  meritorious, 
like  any  other  act  of  virtue:  and  for  this  reason  it  avails 
not  without  charity. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIII. .  A.  6),  the  chief 
act  of  fortitude  is  endurance :  to  this  and  not  to  its  secondary 
act,  which  is  aggression,  martyrdom  belongs.  And  since 
patience  serves  fortitude  on  the  part  of  its  chief  act,  viz. 
endurance,  hence  it  is  that  martyrs  are  also  praised  for  their 
patience. 

Third  Article. 

whether  martyrdom  is  an  act  of  the  greatest 

perfection  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  martyrdom  is  not  an  act  of  the 
greatest  perfection.  For  seemingly  that  which  is  a  matter 
of  counsel  and  not  of  precept  pertains  to  perfection,  because, 
to  wit,  it  is  not  necessary  for  salvation.  But  it  would  seem 
that  martyrdom  is  necessary  for  salvation,  since  the  Apostle 
says  (Rom.  x.  10),  With  the  heart  we  believe  unto  justice,  but 
with  the  mouth  confession  is  made  unto  salvation,  and  it  is 
written  (1  John  iii.  16),  that  we  ought  to  lay  down  our  lives 
for  the  brethren.  Therefore  martyrdom  does  not  pertain  to 
perfection. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  It  seems  to  point  to  greater  perfection 
that  a  man  give  his  soul  to  God,  which  is  done  by  obedience, 
than  that  he  give  God  his  body,  which  is  done  by  martyrdom : 
wherefore   Gregory  says  {Moral,  xxxv.)  that   obedience   is 


Q.  124.  art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  220 

preferable  to   all   sacrifices.     Therefore   martyrdom   is   not 
an  act  of  the  greatest  perfection. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  would  seem  better  to  do  good  to  others 
than  to  maintain  oneself  in  good,  since  the  good  of  the  nation 
is  better  than  the  good  of  the  individual,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  {Ethic,  i.  2).  Now  he  that  suffers  martyrdom 
profits  himself  alone,  whereas  he  that  teaches  does  good  to 
many.  Therefore  the  act  of  teaching  and  guiding  subjects 
is  more  perfect  than  the  act  of  martyrdom. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  (De  Sanct.  Virgin,  xlvi.)  prefers 
martyrdom  to  virginity  which  pertains  to  perfection. 
Therefore  martyrdom  seems  to  belong  to  perfection  in  the 
highest  degree. 

/  answer  that,  We  may  speak  of  an  act  of  virtue  in  two 
ways.  First,  with  regard  to  the  species  of  that  act,  as 
compared  to  the  virtue  proximately  eliciting  it.  In  this 
way  martyrdom,  which  consists  in  the  due  endurance  of 
death,  cannot  be  the  most  perfect  of  virtuous  acts,  because 
endurance  of  death  is  not  praiseworthy  in  itself,  but  only  in  so 
far  as  it  is  directed  to  some  good  consisting  in  an  act  of 
virtue,  such  as  faith  or  the  love  of  God,  so  that  this  act  of 
virtue  being  the  end  is  better. 

A  virtuous  act  may  be  considered  in  another  way,  in 
comparison  with  its  first  motive  cause,  which  is  the  love 
of  charity,  and  it  is  in  this  respect  that  an  act  comes  to 
belong  to  the  perfection  of  life,  since,  as  the  Apostle  says 
(Col.  hi.  14),  that  charity  .  .  .  is  the  bond  of  perfection.  Now, 
of  all  virtuous  acts  martyrdom  is  the  greatest  proof  of  the 
perfection  of  charity:  since  a  man's  love  for  a  thing  is 
proved  to  be  so  much  the  greater,  according  as  that  which 
he  despises  for  its  sake  is  more  dear  to  him,  or  that  which  he 
chooses  to  suffer  for  its  sake  is  more  odious.  But  it  is  evident 
that  of  all  the  goods  of  the  present  life  man  loves  life  itself 
most,  and  on  the  other  hand  he  hates  death  more  than  any- 
thing, especially  when  it  is  accompanied  by  the  pains  of 
bodily  torment,  from  fear  of  which  even  dumb  animals 
refrain  from  the  greatest  pleasures,  as  Augustine  observes 
(QQ.  LXXXIIL,  qu.  36).     And  from  this  point  of  view  it  is 


221  MARTYRDOM  Q.  124.  Art.  3 

clear  that  martyrdom  is  the  most  perfect  of  human  acts 
in  respect  of  its  genus,  as  being  the  sign  of  the  greatest 
charity,  according  to  John.  xv.  13:  Greater  love  than  this 
no  man  hath,  that  a  man  lay  down  his  life  for  his  friends. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  There  is  no  act  of  perfection,  which  is  a 
matter  of  counsel,  but  what  in  certain  cases  is  a  matter  of 
precept,  as  being  necessary  for  salvation.  Thus  Augustine 
declares  (De  Adult.  Conjug.  xiii.)  that  a  man  is  under  the 
obligation  of  observing  continency,  through  the  absence 
or  sickness  of  his  wife.  Hence  it  is  not  contrary  to  the 
perfection  of  martyrdom  if  in  certain  cases  it  be  necessary 
for  salvation,  since  there  are  cases  when  it  is  not  necessary 
for  salvation  to  suffer  martyrdom;  thus  we  read  of  many 
holy  martyrs  who  through  zeal  for  the  faith  or  brotherly 
love  gave  themselves  up  to  martyrdom  of  their  own  accord. 
As  to  these  precepts,  they  are  to  be  understood  as  referring 
to  the  preparation  of  the  mind. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Martyrdom  embraces  the  highest  possible 
degree  of  obedience,  namely  obedience  unto  death;  thus  we 
read  of  Christ  (Phil.  ii.  8)  that  He  became  obedient  unto 
death.  Hence  it  is  evident  that  martyrdom  is  of  itself 
more  perfect  than  obedience  considered  absolutely. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  This  argument  considers  martyrdom  accord- 
ing to  the  proper  species  of  its  act,  whence  it  derives  no 
excellence  over  all  other  virtuous  acts;  thus  neither  is 
fortitude  more  excellent  than  all  virtues. 

Fourth  Article.    , 
whether  death  is  essential  to  martyrdom  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  death  is  not  essential  to  martyr- 
dom. For  Jerome  says  in  a  sermon  on  the  Assumption 
(Epist.  ad  Paul,  et  Eustoch.) :  I  should  say  rightly  that  the 
Mother  of  God  was  both  virgin  and  martyr,  although  she  ended 
her  days  in  peace:  and  Gregory  says  (Horn.  iii.  in  Ev.): 
Although  persecution  has  ceased  to  offer  the  opportunity,  yet 
the  peace  we  enjoy  is  not  without  its  martyrdom,  since  even 


Q.  124.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  222 

if  we  no  longer  yield  the  life  of  the  body  to  the  sword,  yet  do  we 
slay  fleshly  desires  in  the  soul  with  the  sword  of  the  spirit 
Therefore  there  can  be  martyrdom  without  suffering  death. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  We  read  of  certain  women  as  commended 
for  despising  life  for  the  sake  of  safeguarding  the  integrity 
of  the  flesh:  wherefore  seemingly  the  integrity  of  chastity 
is  preferable  to  the  life  of  the  body.  Now  sometimes  the 
integrity  of  the  flesh  has  been  forfeited  or  has  been  threatened 
in  confession  of  the  Christian  faith,  as  in  the  case  of  Agnes 
and  Lucy.  Therefore  it  seems  that  the  name  of  martyr 
should  be  accorded  to  a  woman  who  forfeits  the  integrity 
of  the  flesh  for  the  sake  of  Christ's  faith,  rather  than  if  she 
were  to  forfeit  even  the  life  of  the  body:  wherefore  also 
Lucy  said:  If  thou  causest  me  to  be  violated  against  my  will., 
my  chastity  will  gain  me  a  twofold  crown. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Martyrdom  is  an  act  of  fortitude.  But 
it  belongs  to  fortitude  to  brave  not  only  death  but  also  other 
hardships,  as  Augustine  declares  {Music,  vi.).  Now  there  are 
many  other  hardships  besides  death,  which  one  may  suffer 
for  Christ's  faith,  namely  imprisonment,  exile,  being  stripped 
of  one's  goods,  as  mentioned  in  Heb.  x.  34,  for  which  reason 
we  celebrate  the  martyrdom  of  Pope  Saint  Marcellus, 
notwithstanding  that  he  died  in  prison.  Therefore  it  is 
not  essential  to  martyrdom  that  one  suffer  the  pain  of  death. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Martyrdom  is  a  meritorious  act,  as  stated 
above  (A.  2,  ad  1;  A.  3).  Now  it  cannot  be  a  meritorious 
act  after  death.  Therefore  it  is  before  death;  and  con- 
sequently death  is  not  essential  to  martyrdom. 

On  the  contrary,  Maximus  says  in  a  sermon  on  the  martyrs 
that  in  dying  for  the  faith  he  conquers  who  would  have  been 
vanquished  in  living  without  faith. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  2),  a  martyr  is  so  called 
as  being  a  witness  to  the  Christian  faith,  which  teaches  us 
to  despise  things  visible  for  the  sake  of  things  invisible, 
as  stated  in  Heb.  xi.  Accordingly  it  belongs  to  martyrdom 
that  a  man  bear  witness  to  the  faith  in  showing  by  deed 
that  he  despises  all  things  present,  in  order  to  obtain  in- 
visible goods  to  come.     Now  so  long  as  a  man  retains  the 


223  MARTYRDOM  Q.  124.  Art.  4 

life  of  the  body  he  does  not  show  by  deed  that  he  despises 
all  things  relating  to  the  body.  For  men  are  wont  to  despise 
both  their  kindred  and  all  they  possess,  and  even  to  suffer 
bodily  pain,  rather  than  lose  life.  Hence  Satan  testified 
against  Job  (Job  ii.  4):  Skin  for  skin,  and  all  that  a  man 
hath  he  will  give  for  his  soul  (Douay, — life)  i.e.  for  the  life 
of  his  body.  Therefore  the  perfect  notion  of  martyrdom 
requires  that  a  man  suffer  death  for  Christ's  sake. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  authorities  quoted,  and  the  like  that 
one  may  meet  with,  speak  of  martyrdom  by  way  of  simili- 
tude. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  When  a  woman  forfeits  the  integrity  of  the 
flesh,  or  is  condemned  to  forfeit  it  under  pretext  of  the 
Christian  faith,  it  is  not  evident  to  men  whether  she  suffers 
this  for  love  of  the  Christian  faith,  or  rather  through  con- 
tempt of  chastity.  Wherefore  in  the  sight  of  men  her 
testimony  is  not  held  to  be  sufficient,  and  consequently 
this  is  not  martyrdom  properly  speaking.  In  the  sight  of 
God,  however,  Who  searcheth  the  heart,  this  may  be  deemed 
worthy  of  a  reward,  as  Lucy  said. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  above  (O.  CXXIII.,  AA.  4,  5), 
fortitude  regards  danger  of  death  chiefly,  and  other  dangers 
consequently;  wherefore  a  person  is  not  called  a  martyr 
merely  for  suffering  imprisonment,  or  exile,  or  forfeiture 
of  his  wealth,  except  in  so  far  as  these  result  in  death. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  The  merit  of  martyrdom  is  not  after  death, 
but  in  the  voluntary  endurance  of  death,  namely  in  the 
fact  that  a  person  willingly  suffers  being  put  to  death.  It 
happens  sometimes,  however,  that  a  man  lives  for  some  time 
after  being  mortally  wounded  for  Christ's  sake,  or  after 
suffering  for  the  faith  of  Christ  any  other  kind  of  hardship 
inflicted  by  persecution  and  continued  until  death  ensues. 
The  act  of  martyrdom  is  meritorious  while  a  man  is  in 
this  state,  and  at  the  very  time  that  he  is  suffering  these 
hardships. 


Q.  124.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  224 


Fifth  Article. 

whether  faith  alone  is  the  cause  of 
martyrdom  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  faith  alone  is  the  cause  of 
martyrdom.  For  it  is  written  (1  Pet.  iv.  15,  16):  Let  none 
of  you  suffer  as  a  murderer,  or  a  thief,  or  a  railer,  or  a  coveter 
of  other  men's  things.  But  if  as  a  Christian,  let  him  not  be 
ashamed,  but  let  him  glorify  God  in  this  name.  Now  a  man 
is  said  to  be  a  Christian  because  he  holds  the  faith  of  Christ. 
Therefore  only  faith  in  Christ  gives  the  glory  of  martyrdom 
to  those  who  suffer. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  A  martyr  is  a  kind  of  witness.  But 
witness  is  borne  to  the  truth  alone.  Now  one  is  not  called 
a  martyr  for  bearing  witness  to  any  truth,  but  only  for 
witnessing  to  the  Divine  truth,  otherwise  a  man  would  be 
a  martyr  if  he  were  to  die  for  confessing  a  truth  of  geometry 
or  some  other  speculative  science,  which  seems  ridiculous. 
Therefore  faith  alone  is  the  cause  of  martyrdom. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Those  virtuous  deeds  would  seem  to  be 
of  most  account  which  are  directed  to  the  common  good, 
since  the  good  of  the  nation  is  better  than  the  good  of  the  indi- 
vidual, according  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  i.  2).  If,  then, 
some  other  good  were  the  cause  of  martyrdom,  it  would 
seem  that  before  all  those  would  be  martyrs  who  die  for 
the  defence  of  their  country.  Yet  this  is  not  consistent 
with  Church  observance,  for  we  do  not  celebrate  the  martyr- 
dom of  those  who  die  in  a  just  war.  Therefore  faith  alone 
is  the  cause  of  martyrdom. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Matth.  v.  10):  Blessed  are 
they  that  suffer  persecution  for  justice'  sake,  which  pertains 
to  martyrdom,  according  to  a  gloss,  as  well  as  Jerome's 
commentary  on  this  passage.  Now  not  only  faith  but  also 
the  other  virtues  pertain  to  justice.  Therefore  other 
virtues  can  be  the  cause  of  martyrdom. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  4),  martyrs  are  so 


225  MARTYRDOM  Q.  124.  Art.  5 

called  as  being  witnesses,  because  by  suffering  in  body 
unto  death  they  bear  witness  to  the  truth;  not  indeed  to 
any  truth,  but  to  the  truth  which  is  in  accordance  with 
godliness,  and  was  made  known  to  us  by  Christ:  wherefore 
Christ's  martyrs  are  His  witnesses.  Now  this  truth  is 
the  truth  of  faith.  Wherefore  the  cause  of  all  martyrdom 
is  the  truth  of  faith. 

But  the  truth  of  faith  includes  not  only  inward  belief, 
but  also  outward  profession,  which  is  expressed  not  only 
by  words,  whereby  one  confesses  the  faith,  but  also  by  deeds, 
whereby  a  person  shows  that  he  has  faith,  according  to 
James  ii.  18,  I  will  show  thee,  by  works,  my  faith.  Hence  it 
is  written  of  certain  people  (Tit.  i.  16) :  They  profess  that  they 
know  God  but  in  their  works  they  deny  Him.  Thus  all  virtuous 
deeds,  inasmuch  as  they  are  referred  to  God,  are  professions 
of  the  faith  whereby  we  come  to  know  that  God  requires 
these  works  of  us,  and  rewards  us  for  them:  and  in  this  way 
they  can  be  the  cause  of  martyrdom.  For  this  reason  the 
Church  celebrates  the  martyrdom  of  Blessed  John  the 
Baptist,  who  suffered  death,  not  for  refusing  to  deny  the 
faith,  but  for  reproving  adultery. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  A  Christian  is  one  who  is  Christ's.  Now  a 
person  is  said  to  be  Christ's,  not  only  through  having  faith 
in  Christ,  but  also  because  he  is  actuated  to  virtuous  deeds 
by  the  Spirit  of  Christ,  according  to  Rom.  viii.  9,  If  any  man 
have  not  the  Spirit  of  Christ,  he  is  none  of  His;  and  again 
because  in  imitation  of  Christ  he  is  dead  to  sins,  according  to 
Gal.  v.  24,  They  that  are  Christ's  have  crucified  their  flesh 
with  the  vices  and  concupiscences.  Hence  to  suffer  as  a 
Christian  is  not  only  to  suffer  in  confession  of  the  faith, 
which  is  done  by  words,  but  also  to  suffer  for  doing  any 
good  work,  or  for  avoiding  any  sin,  for  Christ's  sake,  because 
this  all  comes  under  the  head  of  witnessing  to  the  faith. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  truth  of  other  sciences  has  no  connexion 
with  the  worship  of  the  Godhead :  hence  it  is  not  called  truth 
according  to  godliness,  and  consequently  the  confession 
thereof  cannot  be  said  to  be  the  direct  cause  of  martyrdom. 
Yet,  since  every  he  is  a  sin,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CX.,  AA.  3, 4), 

11.  ii.  4  15 


Q.  i24.Art.5    THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  226 

avoidance  of  a  lie,  to  whatever  truth  it  may  be  contrary, 
may  be  the  cause  of  martyrdom  inasmuch  as  a  lie  is  a  sin 
against  the  Divine  Law 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  good  of  one's  country  is  paramount 
among  human  goods:  yet  the  Divine  good,  which  is  the 
proper  cause  of  martyrdom,  is  of  more  account  than  human 
good.  Nevertheless,  since  human  good  may  become  Divine, 
for  instance  when  it  is  referred  to  God,  it  follows  that  any 
human  good  in  so  far  as  it  is  referred  to  God,  may  be  the 
cause  of  martyrdom. 


QUESTION  CXXV. 

OF  FEAR.* 

(In  Four  Articles). 

We  must   now  consider  the   vices   opposed  to  fortitude: 
(i)  Fear;  (2)  Fearlessness;  (3)  Daring. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry: 
(1)  Whether  fear  is  a  sin  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  opposed  to 
fortitude  ?  (3)  Whether  it  is  a  mortal  sin  ?  (4)  Whether 
it  excuses  from  sin,  or  diminishes  it  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  fear  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fear  is  not  a  sin.  For  fear  is  a 
passion,  as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  XXIII. ,  A.  4:  Q.  XLII.) 
Now  we  are  neither  praised  nor  blamed  for  passions,  as  stated 
in  Ethic,  ii.  Since  then  every  sin  is  blameworthy,  it  seems 
that  fear  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Nothing  that  is  commanded  in  the 
Divine  Law  is  a  sin :  since  the  law  of  the  Lord  is  unspotted 
(Ps.  xviii.  8).  Yet  fear  is  commanded  in  God's  law,  for  it  is 
written  (Eph.  vi.  5) :  Servants,  be  obedient  to  them  that  are 
your  lords  according  to  the  flesh,  with  fear  and  trembling. 
Therefore  fear  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Nothing  that  is  naturally  in  man  is  a  sin, 
for  sin  is  contrary  to  nature  according  to  Damascene  (De 

*  S.  Thomas  calls  this  vice  indifferently  fear  or  timidity.  The 
translation  requires  one  to  adhere  to  these  terms  on  account  of  the 
connexion  with  the  passion  of  fear.  Otherwise  cowardice  would  be  a 
better  rendering. 

227 


Q.  125.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  228 

Fide  Orthod.  iii.).  Now  fear  is  natural  to  man:  wherefore 
the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.  7)  that  a  man  would  be 
insane  or  insensible  to  pain,  if  nothing,  not  even  earthquakes 
nor  deluges,  inspired  him  with  fear.  Therefore  fear  is  not  a 
sin.  On  the  contrary,  Our  Lord  said  (Matth.  x.  28) :  Fear  ye 
not  them  that  kill  the  body,  and  it  is  written  (Ezech.  ii.  6) : 
Fear  not,  neither  be  thou  afraid  of  their  words. 

I  answer  that,  A  human  act  is  said  to  be  a  sin  on  account 
of  its  being  inordinate,  because  the  good  of  a  human  act 
consists  in  order,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CIX.,  A.  2:  Q.  CXIV., 
A.  1).  Now  this  due  order  requires  that  the  appetite  be  subject 
to  the  ruling  of  reason .  And  reason  dictates  that  certain  things 
should  be  shunned  and  some  sought  after.  Among  things  to 
be  shunned,  it  dictates  that  some  are  to  be  shunned  more 
than  others ;  and  among  things  to  be  sought  after,  that  some 
are  to  be  sought  after  more  than  others.  Moreover,  the  more 
a  good  is  to  be  sought  after,  the  more  is  the  opposite  evil  to 
be  shunned.  The  result  is  that  reason  dictates  that  certain 
goods  are  to  be  sought  after  more  than  certain  evils  are  to  be 
avoided.  Accordingly  when  the  appetite  shuns  what  the 
reason  dictates  that  we  should  endure  rather  than  forfeit 
others  that  we  should  rather  seek  for,  fear  is  inordinate  and 
sinful.  On  the  other  hand,  when  the  appetite  fears  so  as  to 
shun  what  reason  requires  to  be  shunned,  the  appetite  is 
neither  inordinate  nor  sinful. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Fear  in  its  generic  acceptation  denotes 
avoidance  in  general.  Hence  in  this  way  it  does  not  include 
the  notion  of  good  or  evil:  and  the  same  applies  to  every 
other  passion.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  that  passions 
call  for  neither  praise  nor  blame,  because,  to  wit,  we  neither 
praise  nor  blame  those  who  are  angry  or  afraid,  but  only 
those  who  behave  thus  in  an  ordinate  or  inordinate  manner. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  fear  which  the  Apostle  inculcates  is 
in  accordance  with  reason,  namely  that  servants  should  fear 
lest  they  be  lacking  in  the  service  they  owe  their  masters. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Reason  dictates  that  we  should  shun  the 
evils  that  we  cannot  withstand,  and  the  endurance  of  which 
profits  us  nothing.     Hence  there  is  no  sin  in  fearing  them. 


229  TIMIDITY  Q.  125.  Art  2 

Second  Article, 
whether  the  sin  of  fear  is  contrary  to  fortitude  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  sin  of  fear  is  not  contrary 
to  fortitude:  because  fortitude  is  about  dangers  of  death, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIIL,  AA.  4,  5).  But  the  sin  of  fear 
is  not  always  connected  with  dangers  of  death,  for  a  gloss  on 
Ps.  cxxvii.  1,  Blessed  are  all  they  that  fear  the  Lord,  says  that 
it  is  human  fear  whereby  we  dread  to  suffer  carnal  dangers, 
or  to  lose  worldly  goods.  Again  a  gloss  on  Matth.  xxvii.  44, 
He  prayed  the  third  time,  saying  the  selfsame  word,  says  that 
evil  fear  is  threefold,  fear  of  death,  fear  of  pain,  and  fear  of 
contempt.  Therefore  the  sin  of  fear  is  not  contrary  to 
fortitude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  chief  reason  why  a  man  is  com- 
mended for  fortitude  is  that  he  exposes  himself  to  the  danger 
of  death.  Now  sometimes  a  man  exposes  himself  to  death 
through  fear  of  slavery  or  shame.  Thus  Augustine  relates 
(De  Civ.  Dei  i.)  that  Cato,  in  order  not  to  be  Caesar's  slave, 
gave  himself  up  to  death.  Therefore  the  sin  of  fear  bears 
a  certain  likeness  to  fortitude  instead  of  being  opposed 
thereto. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  All  despair  arises  from  fear.  But 
despair  is  opposed  not  to  fortitude  but  to  hope,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XX.,  A.  1 ;  I.-IL,  Q.  XL.,  A.  4).  Neither  therefore  is 
the  sin  of  fear  opposed  to  fortitude. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  (Ethic,  ii.  7;  iii.  7)  states 
that  timidity  is  opposed  to  fortitude. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XIX.,  A.  3:  I.-IL, 
Q.  XLIIL,  A.  1),  all  fear  arises  from  love;  since  no  one  fears 
save  what  is  contrary  to  something  he  loves.  Now  love  is 
not  confined  to  any  particular  kind  of  virtue  or  vice:  but 
ordinate  love  is  included  in  every  virtue,  since  every 
virtuous  man  loves  the  good  proper  to  his  virtue;  while 
inordinate  love  is  included  in  every  sin,  because  inordinate 
love  gives  use  to  inordinate  desire.     Hence  in  like  manner 


Q.  125.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  230 

inordinate  fear  is  included  in  every  sin;  thus  the  covetous 
man  fears  the  loss  of  money,  the  intemperate  man  the  loss 
of  pleasure,  and  so  on.  But  the  greatest  fear  of  all  is  that 
which  has  the  danger  of  death  for  its  object,  as  we  find 
proved  in  Ethic,  iii.  6.  Wherefore  the  inordinateness  of 
this  fear  is  opposed  to  fortitude  which  regards  dangers  of 
death.  For  this  reason  timidity  is  said  to  be  antonomasti- 
cally*  opposed  to  fortitude. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  passages  quoted  refer  to  inordinate 
fear  in  its  generic  acceptation,  which  can  be  opposed  to 
various  virtues. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Human  acts  are  estimated  chiefly  with  refer- 
ence to  the  end,  as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  I.,  A.  3:  Q.  XVIII., 
A.  6) :  and  it  belongs  to  a  brave  man  to  expose  himself  to 
danger  of  death  for  the  sake  of  a  good.  But  a  man  who 
exposes  himself  to  danger  of  death  in  order  to  escape  from 
slavery  or  hardships  is  overcome  by  fear,  which  is  contrary 
to  fortitude.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.  7), 
that  to  die  in  order  to  escape  poverty,  want,  or  something 
disagreeable  is  an  act  not  of  fortitude  but  of  cowardice:  for 
to  shun  hardships  is  a  mark  of  effeminacy. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.,  XLV.,  A.  2),  fear 
is  the  beginning  of  despair  even  as  hope  is  the  beginning 
of  daring.  Wherefore,  just  as  fortitude  which  employs 
daring  in  moderation  presupposes  hope,  so  on  the  other 
hand  despair  proceeds  from  some  kind  of  fear.  It  does  not 
follow,  however,  that  any  kind  of  despair  results  from  any 
kind  of  fear,  but  that  only  from  fear  of  the  same  kind. 
Now  the  despair  that  is  opposed  to  hope  is  referred  to  another 
kind,  namely  to  Divine  things;  whereas  the  fear  that  is 
opposed  to  fortitude  regards  dangers  of  death.  Hence  the 
argument  does  not  prove. 

*  Antonomasia  is  the  figure  of  speech  whereby  we  substitute  the 
general  for  the  individual  term;  e.g.  The  Philosopher  for  Aristotle: 
and  so  timidity,  which  is  inordinate  fear  of  any  evil,  is  employed  to 
denote  inordinate  fear  of  the  danger  of  death. 


231  TIMIDITY  Q.  125.  Art  3 

Third  Article, 
whether  fear  is  a  mortal  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fear  is  not  a  mortal  sin.  For, 
as  stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  XXIII.,  A.  1),  fear  is  in  the  irascible 
faculty  which  is  a  part  of  the  sensuality.  Now  there  is 
none  but  venial  sin  in  the  sensuality,  as  stated  above  (I.-IL, 
Q.  LXXIV.,  A.  4).     Therefore  fear  is  not  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Every  mortal  sin  turns  the  heart  wholly 
from  God.  But  fear  does  not  this,  for  a  gloss  on  Judges  vii.  3, 
Whosoever  is  fearful,  etc.,  says  that  a  man  is  fearful  when 
he  trembles  at  the  very  thought  of  conflict;  yet  he  is  not  so  wholly 
terrified  at  heart,  but  that  he  can  rally  and  take  courage. 
Therefore  fear  is  not  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Mortal  sin  is  a  lapse  not  only  from 
perfection  but  also  from  a  precept.  But  fear  does  not  make 
one  lapse  from  a  precept,  but  only  from  perfection;  for  a 
gloss  on  Deut.  xx.  9,  What  man  is  there  that  is  fearful  and 
fainthearted  ?  says:  We  learn  from  this  that  no  man  can  take 
%p  the  profession  of  contemplation  or  spiritual  warfare,  if  he, 
still  fears  to  be  despoiled  of  earthly  riches.  Therefore  fear  is 
not  a  mortal  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  For  mortal  sin  alone  is  the  pain  of  hell 
due:  and  yet  this  is  due  to  the  fearful,  according  to 
Apoc.  xxi.  8,  But  the  fearful  and  unbelieving  and  the  abomin- 
able, etc.,  shall  have  their  portion  in  the  pool  burning  with  fire 
and  brimstone  which  is  the  second  death.  Therefore  fear  is  a 
mortal  sin. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  1),  fear  is  a  sin  through 
being  inordinate,  that  is  to  say,  through  shunning  what 
ought  not  to  be  shunned  according  to  reason.  Now  some- 
times this  inordinateness  of  fear  is  confined  to  the  sensitive 
appetites,  without  the  accession  of  the  rational  appetite's 
consent :  and  then  it  cannot  be  a  mortal,  but  only  a  venial 
sin.  But  sometimes  this  inordinateness  of  fear  reaches 
to   the   rational  appetite  which  is    called  the  will,  which 


Q.  MS- Art.  3    THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA"  232 

deliberately  shuns  something  against  the  dictate  of  reason : 
and  this  inordinateness  of  fear  is  sometimes  a  mortal,  some- 
times a  venial  sin.  For  if  a  man  through  fear  of  the  danger 
of  death  or  of  any  other  temporal  evil  is  so  disposed  as  to 
do  what  is  forbidden,  or  Lo  omit  what  is  commanded  by  the 
Divine  law,  such  fear  is  a  mortal  sin :  otherwise  it  is  a  venial 
sin. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  argument  considers  fear  as  confined 
to  the  sensuality. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  gloss  also  can  be  understood  as  referring 
to  the  fear  that  is  confined  within  the  sensuality.  Or 
better  still  we  may  reply  that  a  man  is  terrified  with  his 
whole  heart  when  fear  banishes  his  courage  beyond  remedy. 
Now  even  when  fear  is  a  mortal  sin,  it  may  happen  never- 
theless that  one  is  not  so  wilfully  terrified  that  one  cannot 
be  persuaded  to  put  fear  aside :  thus  sometimes  a  man  sins 
mortally  by  consenting  to  concupiscence,  and  is  turned 
aside  from  accomplishing  what  he  purposed  doing. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  This  gloss  speaks  of  the  fear  that  turns  man 
aside  from  a  good  that  is  necessary,  not  for  the  fulfilment 
of  a  precept,  but  for  the  perfection  of  a  counsel.  Suchlike 
fear  is  not  a  mortal  sin,  but  is  sometimes  venial:  and  some- 
times it  is  not  a  sin,  for  instance  when  one  has  a  reasonable 
cause  for  fear. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  fear  excuses  from  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fear  does  not  excuse  from  sin. 
For  fear  is  a  sin,  as  stated  above  (A.  1).  But  sin  does  not 
excuse  from  sin,  rather  does  it  aggravate  it.  Therefore 
fear  does  not  excuse  from  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  If  any  fear  excuses  from  sin,  most  of  all 
would  this  be  true  of  the  fear  of  death,  to  which,  as  the 
saying  is,  a  courageous  man  is  subject.  Yet  this  fear, 
seemingly,  is  no  excuse,  because,  since  death  comes,  of 
necessity,  to  all,  it  does  not  seem  to  be  an  object  of  fear. 
Therefore  fear  does  not  excuse  from  sin. 


233  TIMIDITY  Q.  125.  Art.  4 

Obj.  3.  Further,  All  fear  is  of  evil,  either  temporal  or 
spiritual.  Now  fear  of  spiritual  evil  cannot  excuse  sin, 
because  instead  of  inducing  one  to  sin,  it  withdraws  one 
from  sin:  and  fear  of  temporal  evil  does  not  excuse  from 
sin,  because  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iii.  6)  one 
should  not  fear  poverty,  nor  sickness,  nor  anything  that  is  not 
a  result  of  one's  own  wickedness.  Therefore  it  seems  that 
in  no  sense  does  fear  excuse  from  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  stated  in  the  Decretals  (I.,  Q.  I.,  Cap. 
Constat.):  A  man  who  has  been  forcibly  and  unwillingly 
ordained  by  heretics,  has  an  ostensible  excuse. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  3),  fear  is  sinful  in  so 
far  as  it  runs  counter  to  the  order  of  reason.  Now  reason 
judges  certain  evils  to  be  shunned  rather  than  others. 
Wherefore  it  is  no  sin  not  to  shun  what  is  less  to  be  shunned 
in  order  to  avoid  what  reason  judges  to  be  more  avoided: 
thus  death  of  the  body  is  more  to  be  avoided  than  the  loss 
of  temporal  goods.  Hence  a  man  would  be  excused  from 
sin  if  through  fear  of  death  he  were  to  promise  or  give 
something  to  a  robber,  and  yet  he  would  be  guilty  of  sin 
were  he  to  give  to  sinners,  rather  than  to  the  good  to  whom 
he  should  give  in  preference.  On  the  other  hand,  if  through 
fear  a  man  were  to  avoid  evils  which  according  to  reason 
are  less  to  be  avoided,  and  so  incur  evils  which  according 
to  reason  are  more  to  be  avoided,  he  could  not  be  wholly 
excused  from  sin,  because  suchlike  fear  would  be  inordinate. 
Now  the  evils  of  the  soul  are  more  to  be  feared  than  the  evils 
of  the  body ;  and  evils  of  the  body  more  than  evils  of  external 
things.  Wherefore  if  one  were  to  incur  evils  of  the  soul, 
namely  sins,  in  order  to  avoid  evils  of  the  body,  such  as 
blows  or  death,  or  evils  of  external  things,  such  as  loss  of 
money;  or  if  one  were  to  endure  evils  of  the  body  in  order 
to  avoid  loss  of  money,  one  would  not  be  wholly  excused 
from  sin.  Yet  one's  sin  would  be  extenuated  somewhat, 
for  what  is  done  through  fear  is  less  voluntary,  because 
when  fear  lays  hold  of  a  man  he  is  under  a  certain  necessity 
of  doing  a  certain  thing.  Hence  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iii.  1) 
says  that  these  things  that  are  done  through  fear  are  not 


Q.  125.  Aet.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  234 

simply  voluntary,  but  a  mixture  of  voluntary  and  in- 
voluntary. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Fear  excuses,  not  in  the  point  of  its  sinful- 
ness, but  in  the  point  of  its  involuntariness. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Although  death  comes,  of  necessity,  to  all, 
yet  the  shortening  of  temporal  life  is  an  evil  and  conse- 
quently an  object  of  fear. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  According  to  the  opinion  of  Stoics,  who  held 
temporal  goods  not  to  be  man's  goods,  it  follows  in  con- 
sequence that  temporal  evils  are  not  man's  evils,  and  that 
therefore  they  are  nowise  to  be  feared.  But  according  to 
Augustine  (De  Lib.  Arb.  ii.)  these  temporal  things  are 
goods  of  the  least  account,  and  this  was  also  the  opinion 
of  the  Peripatetics.  Hence  their  contraries  are  indeed  to 
be  feared;  but  not  so  much  that  one  ought  for  their  sake 
to  renounce  that  which  is  good  according  to  virtue. 


QUESTION  CXXVI. 

OF  FEARLESSNESS. 
(In  Two  Articles). 

We  must  now  consider  the  vice  of  fearlessness :  under  which 
head  there  are  two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  it  is  a 
sin  to  be  fearless  ?    (2)  Whether  it  is  opposed  to  fortitude  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  fearlessness  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fearlessness  is  not  a  sin.  For 
that  which  is  reckoned  to  the  praise  of  a  just  man  is  not 
a  sin.  Now  it  is  written  in  praise  of  the  just  man  (Prov. 
xxviii.  1):  The  just,  bold  as  a  lion,  shall  be  without  dread. 
Therefore  it  is  not  a  sin  to  be  without  fear. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Nothing  is  so  fearful  as  death,  according 
to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iii.  6).  Yet  one  ought  not  to  fear 
even  death,  according  to  Matth.  x.  28,  Fear  ye  not  them  that 
kill  the  body,  etc,  nor  anything  that  can  be  inflicted  by  man, 
according  to  Isa.  li.  12,  Who  art  thou,  that  thou  shouldst  be 
afraid  of  a  mortal  man  ?  Therefore  it  is  not  a  sin  to  be 
fearless. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Fear  is  born  of  love,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXXV.,  A.  2).  Now  it  belongs  to  the  perfection  of 
virtue  to  love  nothing  earthly,  since  according  to  Augustine 
(De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.),  the  love  of  God  to  the  abasement  of  self 
makes  us  citizens  of  the  heavenly  city.  Therefore  it  is  seem- 
ingly not  a  sin  to  fear  nothing  earthly. 

235 


Q.  126.  Art.  1     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  236 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  said  of  the  unjust  judge  (Luke  xviii.  2) 
that  he  feared  not  God  nor  regarded  man. 

I  answer  that,  Since  fear  is  born  of  love,  we  must  seemingly 
judge  alike  of  love  and  fear.  Now  it  is  here  a  question  of 
that  fear  whereby  one  dreads  temporal  evils,  and  which 
results  from  the  love  of  temporal  goods.  And  every  man 
has  it  instilled  in  him  by  nature  to  love  his  own  life  and 
whatever  is  directed  thereto;  and  to  do  so  in  due  measure, 
that  is,  to  love  these  things  not  as  placing  his  end  therein, 
but  as  things  to  be  used  for  the  sake  of  his  last  end.  Hence 
it  is  contrary  to  the  natural  inclination,  and  therefore  a  sin, 
to  fall  short  of  loving  them  in  due  measure.  Nevertheless, 
one  never  lapses  entirely  from  this  love:  since  what  is 
natural  cannot  be  wholly  lost :  for  which  reason  the  Apostle 
says  (Eph.  v.  29) :  No  man  ever  hated  his  own  flesh.  Where- 
fore even  those  that  slay  themselves  do  so  from  love  of 
their  own  flesh,  which  they  desire  to  free  from  present 
stress.  Hence  it  may  happen  that  a  man  fears  death  and 
other  temporal  evils  less  than  he  ought,  for  the  reason  that 
he  loves  them*  less  than  he  ought.  But  that  he  fear  none 
of  these  things  cannot  result  from  an  entire  lack  of  lcve, 
but  only  from  the  fact  that  he  thinks  it  impossible  for  him 
to  be  afflicted  by  the  evils  contrary  to  the  goods  he  loves. 
This  is  sometimes  the  result  of  pride  of  soul  presuming  on 
self  and  despising  others,  according  to  the  saying  of 
Job  xli.  24,  25:  He  (Vulg., — who)  was  made  to  fear  no  one, 
he  beholdeth  every  high  thing :  and  sometimes  it  happens 
through  a  defect  in  the  reason;  thus  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic,  iii.  7)  that  the  Celts.,  through  lack  of  intelligence,  fear 
nothing.^  It  is  therefore  evident  that  fearlessness  is  a  vice, 
whether  it  result  from  lack  of  love,  pride  of  soul,  or  dulness 
of  understanding:  yet  the  latter  is  excused  from  sin  if  it  be 
invincible. 

*  Viz.,  the  contrary  goods.  One  would  expect  se  instead  of  ea. 
We  should  then  read:  For  the  reason  that  he  loves  himself  less 
than  he  ought. 

t  "A  man  would  deserve  to  be  called  insane  and  senseless  if  there 
were  nothing  that  he  feared,  not  even  an  earthquake  nor  a  storm  at  sea, 
as  is  said  to  be  the  case  with  the  Celts." 


237  FEARLESSNESS  Q.  126.  Art.  2 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  just  man  is  praised  for  being  without 
fear  that  withdraws  him  from  good;  not  that  he  is  altogether 
fearless,  for  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  i.  28) :  He  that  is  without 
fear  cannot  be  justified. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Death  and  whatever  else  can  be  inflicted 
by  mortal  man  are  not  to  be  feared  so  that  they  make  us 
forsake  justice:  but  they  are  to  be  feared  as  hindering  man 
in  acts  of  virtue,  either  as  regards  himself,  or  as  regards 
the  progress  he  may  cause  in  others.  Hence  it  is  written 
(Prov.  xiv.  16):  A  wise  man  feareth  and  declineth  from  evil. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Temporal  goods  are  to  be  despised  as 
hindering  us  from  loving  and  serving  God,  and  on  the  same 
score  they  are  not  to  be  feared;  wherefore  it  is  written 
(Ecclus.  xxxiv.  16) :  He  that  feareth  the  Lord  shall  tremble 
at  nothing.  But  temporal  goods  are  not  to  be  despised, 
in  so  far  as  they  are  helping  us  instrument  ally  to  attain 
those  things  that  pertain  to  Divine  fear  and  love. 

Second  Article, 
whether  fearlessness  is  opposed  to  fortitude  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fearlessness  is  not  opposed  to 
fortitude.  For  we  judge  of  habits  by  their  acts.  Now  no 
act  of  fortitude  is  hindered  by  a  man  being  fearless:  since 
if  fear  be  removed,  one  is  both  brave  to  endure,  and  daring 
to  attack.  Therefore  fearlessness  is  not  opposed  to  forti- 
tude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Fearlessness  is  a  vice,  either  through 
lack  of  due  love,  or  on  account  of  pride,  or  by  reason  of 
folly.  Now  lack  of  due  love  is  opposed  to  charity,  pride 
is  contrary  to  humility,  and  folly  to  prudence  or  wisdom. 
Therefore  the  vice  of  fearlessness  is  not  opposed  to  fortitude. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Vices  are  opposed  to  virtue  and  extremes 
to  the  mean.  But  one  mean  has  only  one  extreme  on  the 
one  side.  Since  then  fortitude  has  fear  opposed  to  it  on 
the  one  side  and  daring  on  the  other,  it  seems  that  fearless- 
ness is  not  opposed  thereto. 


Q. 126.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  238 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  {Ethic,  iii.)  reckons 
fearlessness  to  be  opposed  to  fortitude. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  3),  fortitude 
is  concerned  about  fear  and  daring.  Now  every  moral 
virtue  observes  the  rational  mean  in  the  matter  about  which 
it  is  concerned.  Hence  it  belongs  to  fortitude  that  man 
should  moderate  his  fear  according  to  reason,  namely  that 
he  should  fear  what  he  ought,  and  when  he  ought,  and  so 
forth.  Now  this  mode  of  reason  may  be  corrupted  either 
by  excess  or  by  deficiency.  Wherefore  just  as  timidity  is 
opposed  to  fortitude  by  excess  of  fear,  in  so  far  as  a  man 
fears  what  he  ought  not,  and  as  he  ought  not,  so  too  fear- 
lessness is  opposed  thereto  by  deficiency  of  fear,  in  so  far 
as  a  man  fears  not  what  he  ought  to  fear. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  act  of  fortitude  is  to  endure  death 
without  fear,  and  to  be  aggressive,  not  anyhow,  but  accord- 
ing to  reason:  this  the  fearless  man  does  not  do. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Fearlessness  by  its  specific  nature  corrupts 
the  mean  of  fortitude,  wherefore  it  is  opposed  to  fortitude 
directly.  But  in  respect  of  its  causes  nothing  hinders  it 
from  being  opposed  to  other  virtues. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  vice  of  daring  is  opposed  to  fortitude 
by  excess  of  daring,  and  fearlessness  by  deficiency  of  fear. 
Fortitude  imposes  the  mean  on  each  passion.  Hence  there 
is  nothing  unreasonable  in  its  having  different  extremes 
in  different  respects. 


QUESTION  CXXVII. 

OF  DARING.* 

(In    Two    Articles). 

We  must  now  consider  daring;  and  under  this  head  there  are 
two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  daring  is  a  sin? 
(2)  Whether  it  is  opposed  to  fortitude  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  daring  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  daring  is  not  a  sin.  For  it  is 
written  (Job.  xxxix.  21)  concerning  the  horse,  by  which 
according  to  Gregory  (Moral,  xxxi.)  the  godly  preacher  is 
denoted,  that  he goeth  forth  boldly  to  meet  armed  men*  But 
no  vice  redounds  to  a  man's  praise.  Therefore  it  is  not  a  sin 
to  be  daring. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  According  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  vi.  9), 
one  should  take  counsel  in  thought,  and  do  quickly  what  has 
been  counselled.  But  daring  helps  this  quickness  in  doing* 
Therefore  daring  is  not  sinful  but  praiseworthy. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Daring  is  a  passion  caused  by  hope,  as 
stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  XLV.,  A.  2)  when  we  were  treating 
of  the  passions.  But  hope  is  accounted  not  a  sin  but  a 
virtue.  Neither  therefore  should  daring  be  accounted  a 
sin. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ecclus.  viii.  18) :  Go  not  on 
the  way  with  a  bold  man,  lest  he  burden  thee  with  his  evils.     Now 

*  Excessive  daring  or  foolhardiness. 

t  Vulg., — he  pranceth  boldly,  he  goeth  forth  to  meet  armed  men. 

239 


Q.  127.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  240 

no  man's  fellowship  is  to  be  avoided  save  on  account  of  sin. 
Therefore  daring  is  a  sin. 

J  answer  that,  Daring,  as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  XXIII. , 
A.  1:  Q.  LV.),  is  a  passion.  Now  a  passion  is  sometimes 
moderated  according  to  reason,  and  sometimes  it  lacks 
moderation,  either  by  caress  or  by  deficiency,  and  on  this 
account  the  passion  is  sinful.  Again,  the  names  of  the 
passions  are  sometimes  employed  in  the  sense  of  excess, 
thus  we  speak  of  anger  meaning  not  any  but  excessive 
anger,  in  which  case  it  is  sinful,  and  in  the  same  way  daring 
as  implying  excess  is  accounted  a  sin. 

Reply  Oh 7.  1.  The  daring  spoken  of  there  is  that  which  is 
moderated  by  reason,  for  in  that  sense  it  belongs  to  the 
virtue  of  fortitude. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  is  praiseworthy  to  act  quickly  after  taking 
counsel,  which  is  an  act  of  reason.  But  to  wish  to  act 
quickly  before  taking  counsel  is  not  praiseworthy  but  sinful; 
for  this  would  be  to  act  rashly,  which  is  a  vice  contrary  to 
prudence,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LVIIL,  A.  3).  Wherefore 
daring  which  leads  one  to  act  quickly  is  so  far  praiseworthy 
as  it  is  directed  by  reason. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Some  vices  are  unnamed,  and  so  also 
are  some  virtues,  as  the  Philosopher  remarks  {Ethic.  ii,  7; 
iv.  4,  5,  6).  Hence  the  names  of  certain  passions  have  to  be 
applied  to  certain  vices  and  virtues :  and  in  order  to  designate 
vices  we  employ  especially  the  names  of  those  passions  the 
object  of  which  is  an  evil,  as  in  the  case  of  hatred,  fear,  anger 
and  daring.  But  hope  and  love  have  a  good  for  this  object, 
and  so  we  use  them  rather  to  designate  virtues. 


Second  Article, 
whether  daring  is  opposed  to  fortitude? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  daring  is  not  opposed  to  forti- 
tude. For  excess  of  daring  seems  to  result  from  presump- 
tion of  mind.     But  presumption  pertains  to  pride  which  is 


241  DARING  Q.  127.  Art.  2 

opposed  to  humility.  Therefore  daring  is  opposed  to 
humility  rather  than  to  fortitude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Daring  does  not  seem  to  call  for  blame, 
except  in  so  far  as  it  results  in  harm  either  to  the  daring 
person  who  puts  himself  in  danger  inordinately,  or  to  others 
whom  he  attacks  with  daring,  or  exposes  to  danger.  But 
this  seemingly  pertains  to  injustice.  Therefore  daring,  as 
designating  a  sin,  is  opposed,  not  to  fortitude  but  to 
justice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Fortitude  is  concerned  about  fear  and 
daring,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  3).  Now  since 
timidity  is  opposed  to  fortitude  in  respect  of  an  excess  of 
fear,  there  is  another  vice  opposed  to  timidity  in  respect  of 
a  lack  of  fear.  If  then,  daring  is  opposed  to  fortitude,  in  the 
point  of  excessive  daring,  there  will  likewise  be  a  vice  opposed 
to  it  in  the  point  of  deficient  daring.  But  there  is  no  such 
vice.  Therefore  neither  should  daring  be  accounted  a  vice 
in  opposition  to  fortitude. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  in  both  the  Second  and 
Third  Books  of  Ethics  accounts  daring  to  be  opposed  to 
fortitude. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXVL,  A.  2),  it  belongs 
to  a  moral  virtue  to  observe  the  rational  mean  in  the  matter 
about  which  it  is  concerned.  Wherefore  every  vice  that 
denotes  lack  of  moderation  in  the  matter  of  a  moral  virtue  is 
opposed  to  that  virtue,  as  immoderate  to  moderate.  Now 
daring,  in  so  far  as  it  denotes  a  vice,  implies  excess  of  passion, 
and  this  excess  goes  by  the  name  of  daring.  Wherefore  it  is 
evident  that  it  is  opposed  to  the  virtue  of  fortitude  which  is 
concerned  about  fear  and  daring,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIL, 

A.  3)- 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Opposition  between  vice  and  virtue  does  not 
depend  chiefly  on  the  cause  of  the  vice  but  on  the  vice's 
very  species.  Wherefore  it  is  not  necessary  that  daring 
be  opposed  to  the  same  virtue  as  presumption  which  is  its 
cause. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Just  as  the  direct  opposition  of  a  vice  does 
not  depend  on  its  cause,  so  neither  does  it  depend  on  its 

11.  ii.  4  16 


Q.  127.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  242 

effect.     Now  the  harm  done  by  daring  is  its  effect.     Where- 
fore neither  does  the  opposition  of  daring  depend  on  this. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  movement  of  daring  consists  in  a  man 
taking  the  offensive  against  that  which  is  in  opposition  to 
him :  and  nature  inclines  him  to  do  this  except  in  so  far  as 
such  inclination  is  hindered  by  the  fear  of  receiving  harm  from 
that  source.  Hence  the  vice  which  exceeds  in  daring  has  no 
contrary  deficiency,  save  only  timidity.  Yet  daring  does 
not  always  accompany  so  great  a  lack  of  timidity,  for  as 
the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.  7),  the  daring  are  precipitate 
and  eager  to  meet  danger,  yet  fail  when  the  danger  is  present, 
namely  through  fear. 


QUESTION  CXXVIII. 

OF  THE  PARTS  OF  FORTITUDE. 

We  must  now  consider  the  parts  of  fortitude :  first  we  shall 
consider  what  are  the  parts  of  fortitude;  and  secondly  we 
shall  treat  of  each  part. 

Article. 

whether  the  parts  of  fortitude  are  suitably 

assigned  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  parts  of  fortitude  are 
unsuitably  assigned.  For  Tully  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  assigns 
four  parts  to  fortitude,  namely  magnificence,  confidence, 
patience,  and  perseverance.  Now  magnificence  seems  to 
pertain  to  liberality;  since  both  are  concerned  about 
money,  and  a  magnificent  man  must  needs  be  liberal, 
as  the  Philosopher  observes  {Ethic,  iv.  2).  But  liberality 
is  a  part  of  justice,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CXVIL,  A.  5).  There- 
fore magnificence  should  not  be  reckoned  a  part  of  fortitude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  confidence  is  apparently  the  same  as 
hope.  But  hope  does  not  seem  to  pertain  to  fortitude, 
but  is  rather  a  virtue  by  itself.  Therefore  confidence  should 
not  be  reckoned  a  part  of  fortitude. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Fortitude  makes  a  man  behave  aright 
in  face  of  danger.  But  magnificence  and  confidence  do  not 
essentially  imply  any  relation  to  danger.  Therefore  they 
are  not  suitably  reckoned  as  parts  of  fortitude. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  According  to  Tully  (loc.  cit.)  patience 
denotes  endurance  of  hardships,  and  he  ascribes  the  same 
to  fortitude.  Therefore  patience  is  the  same  as  fortitude 
and  not  a  part  thereof. 

243 


Q.  128  THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  244 

Obj.  5.  Further,  that  which  is  a  requisite  to  every  virtue 
should  not  be  reckoned  a  part  of  a  special  virtue.  But 
perseverance  is  required  in  every  virtue:  for  it  is  written 
(Matth.  xxiv.  13) :  He  that  shall  persevere  to  the  end  he 
shall  be  saved.  Therefcre  perseverance  should  not  be 
accounted  a  part  of  fortitude. 

Obj.  6.  Further,  Macrobius  {De  Somn.  Scip.  i.)  reckons 
seven  parts  of  fortitude,  namely  magnanimity,  confidence, 
security,  magnificence,  constancy,  forbearance,  stability. 
Andronicus  also  reckons  seven  virtues  annexed  to  fortitude, 
and  these  are,  courage,  strength  of  will,  magnanimity,  manli- 
ness, perseverance,  magnificence.  Therefore  it  seems  that 
Tully's  reckoning  of  the  parts  of  fortitude  is  incomplete. 

Obj.  7.  Further,  Aristotle  {Ethic,  iii.)  reckons  five  parts  of 
fortitude.  The  first  is  civic  fortitude,  which  produces 
brave  deeds  through  fear  of  dishonour  or  punishmen 
the  second  is  military  fortitude,  which  produces  brave  deeds 
as  a  result  of  warlike  art  or  experience;  the  third  is  the 
fortitude  which  produces  brave  deeds  resulting  from  passion, 
especially  anger;  the  fourth  is  the  fortitude  which  makes  a 
man  act  bravely  through  being  accustomed  to  overcome; 
the  fifth  is  the  fortitude  which  makes  a  man  act  bravely 
through  being  unaccustomed  to  danger.  Now  these  kinds 
of  fortitude  are  not  comprised  under  any  of  the  above 
enumerations.  Therefore  these  enumerations  of  the  parts 
of  fortitude  are  unfitting. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XLVIII.),  a  virtue 
can  have  three  kinds  of  parts,  subjective,  integral,  and 
potential.  But  fortitude,  taken  as  a  special  virtue,  cannot 
have  subjective  parts,  since  it  is  not  divided  into  several 
specifically  distinct  virtues,  for  it  is  about  a  very  special 
matter. 

However,  there  are  quasi-integral  and  potential  parts 
assigned  to  it:  integral  parts,  with  regard  to  those  things 
the  concurrence  of  which  is  requisite  for  an  act  of  fortitude ; 
and  potential  parts,  because  what  fortitude  practises  in  face 
of  the  greatest  hardships,  namely  dangers  of  death,  certain 
other  virtues  practise  in  the  matter  of  certain  minor  hard- 


245  PARTS  OF  FORTITUDE  Q.  128 

ships  and  these  virtues  are  annexed  to  fortitude  as  secondary 
virtues  to  the  principal  virtue.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIII- 
AA.  3,  6),  the  act  of  fortitude  is  twofold,  aggression  and 
endurance.  Now  two  things  are  required  for  the  act  of 
aggression.  The  first  regards  preparation  of  the  mind, 
and  consists  in  one's  having  a  mind  ready  for  aggression. 
In  this  respect  Tully  mentions  confidence,  of  which  he  says 
(loc.  cit.)  that  with  this  the  mind  is  much  assured  and  firmly 
hopeful  in  great  and  honourable  undertakings.  The  second 
regards  the  accomplishment  of  the  deed,  and  consists  in 
not  failing  to  accomplish  what  one  has  confidently  begun.  In 
this  respect  Tully  mentions  magnificence,  which  he  describes 
as  being  the  discussion  and  administration,  i.e.,  accomplish- 
ment of  great  and  lofty  undertakings,  with  a  certain  broad 
and  noble  purpose  of  mind,  so  as  to  combine  execution  with 
greatness  of  purpose.  Accordingly  if  these  two  be  confined 
to  the  proper  matter  of  fortitude,  namely  to  dangers  of 
death,  they  will  be  quasi-integral  parts  thereof,  because 
without  them  there  can  be  no  fortitude;  whereas  if  they 
be  referred  to  other  matters  involving  less  hardship,  they 
will  be  virtues  specifically  distinct  from  fortitude,  but  annexed 
thereto  as  secondary  virtues  to  principal :  thus  magnificence 
is  referred  by  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  iv.)  to  great  expenses, 
and  magnanimity,  which  seems  to  be  the  same  as  confidence, 
to  great  honours.  Again,  two  things  are  requisite  for  the 
other  act  of  fortitude,  viz.  endurance.  The  first  is  that  the 
mind  be  not  broken  by  sorrow,  and  fall  away  from  its  great- 
ness, by  reason  of  the  stress  of  threatening  evil.  In  this 
respect  he  mentions  patience,  which  he  describes  as  the  volun- 
tary and  prolonged  endurance  of  arduous  and  difficult  things  for 
the  sake  of  virtue  or  profit.  The  other  is  that  by  the  prolonged 
suffering  of  hardships  man  be  not  wearied  so  as  to  lose 
courage,  according  to  Heb.  xii.  3.,  That  you  be  not  wearied, 
fainting  in  your  minds.  In  this  respect  he  mentions  per- 
severance, which  accordingly  he  describes  as  the  fixed  and 
continued  persistence  in  a  well  considered  purpose.  If  these 
two  be  confined  to  the  proper  matter  of  fortitude,  they 
will  be  quasi-integral  parts  thereof;  but  if  they  be  referred 


Q.  128  THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  246 

to  any  kind  of  hardship  they  will  be  virtues  distinct  from 
fortitude,  yet  annexed  thereto  as  secondary  to  principal. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Magnificence  in  the  matter  of  liberality 
adds  a  certain  greatness:  this  is  connected  with  the  notion 
of  difficulty  which  is  the  object  of  the  irascible  faculty,  that 
is  perfected  chiefly  by  fortitude:  and  to  this  virtue,  in  this 
respect,  it  belongs. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Hope  whereby  one  confides  in  God  is 
accounted  a  theological  virtue,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XVII., 
A.  5;  I. -II.,  Q.  LXIL,  A.  3).  But  by  confidence  which 
here  is  accounted  a  part  of  fortitude,  man  hopes  in  himself, 
yet  under  God  withal. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  To  venture  on  anything  great  seems  to 
involve  danger,  since  to  fail  in  such  things  is  very  disastrous. 
Wherefore  although  magnificence  and  confidence  are 
referred  to  the  accomplishment  of  or  venturing  on  any  other 
great  things,  they  have  a  certain  connexion  with  fortitude 
by  reason  of  the  imminent  danger. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Patience  endures  not  only  dangers  of 
death,  with  which  fortitude  is  concerned,  without  excessive 
sorrow,  but  also  any  other  hardships  or  dangers.  In 
this  respect  it  is  accounted  a  virtue  annexed  to  fortitude: 
but  as  referred  to  dangers  of  death,  it  is  an  integral  part 
thereof. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  Perseverance  as  denoting  persistence  in  a 
good  deed  unto  the  end,  may  be  a  circumstance  of  every 
virtue,  but  it  is  reckoned  a  part  of  fortitude  in  the  sense 
stated  in  the  body  of  the  Article. 

Reply  Obj.  6.  Macrobius  reckons  the  four  aforesaid 
mentioned  by  Tully,  namely  confidence,  magnificence, 
forbearance,  which  he  puts  in  the  place  of  patience,  and 
firmness,  which  he  substitutes  for  perseverance.  And  he 
adds  three,  two  of  which,  namely  magnanimity  and  security, 
are  comprised  by  Tully  under  the  head  of  confidence.  But 
Macrobius  is  more  specific  in.  his  enumeration.  Because 
confidence  denotes  a  man's  hope  for  great  things :  and  hope 
for  anything  presupposes  an  appetite  stretching  forth  to 
great  things  by  desire,  and  this  belongs  to  magnanimity. 


247  PARTS  OF  FORTITUDE  Q.  128 

For  it  has  been  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  XL.,  A.  2)  that  hope 
presupposes  love  and  desire  of  the  thing  hoped  for. 

A  still  better  reply  is  that  confidence  pertains  to  the 
certitude  of  hope;  while  magnanimity  refers  to  the  magni- 
tude of  the  thing  hoped  for.  Now  hope  has  no  firmness 
unless  its  contrary  be  removed,  for  sometimes  one,  for  one's 
own  part,  would  hope  for  something,  but  hope  is  avoided  on 
account  of  the  obstacle  of  fear,  since  fear  is  somewhat 
contrary  to  hope,  as  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  XL.,  A.  4,  ad  1). 
Hence  Macrobius  adds  security,  which  banishes  fear.  He 
adds  a  third,  namely  constancy,  which  may  be  comprised 
under  magnificence.  For  in  performing  deeds  of  magnifi- 
cence one  needs  to  have  a  constant  mind.  For  this  reason 
Tully  says  that  magnificence  consists  not  only  in  accomplish- 
ing great  things,  but  also  in  discussing  them  generously 
in  the  mind.  Constancy  may  also  pertain  to  perseverance, 
so  that  one  may  be  called  persevering  through  not  desisting 
on  account  of  delays,  and  constant  through  not  desisting 
on  account  of  any  other  obstacles. 

Those  that  are  mentioned  by  Andronicus  seem  to  amount 
to  the  same  as  the  above.  For  with  Tully  and  Macrobius 
he  mentions  perseverance  and  magnificence,  and  with  Macro- 
bius, magnanimity.  Strength  of  will  is  the  same  as  patience 
or  forbearance,  for  he  says  that  strength  of  will  is  a  habit 
that  makes  one  ready  to  attempt  what  ought  to  be  attempted, 
and  to  endure  what  reason  says  should  be  endured — i.e.  good 
courage  seems  to  be  the  same  as  assurance,  for  he  defines 
it  as  strength  of  soul  in  the  accomplishment  of  its  purpose. 
Manliness  is  apparently  the  same  as  confidence,  for  he  says 
that  manliness  is  a  habit  of  self-sufficiency  in  matters  of 
virtue.  Besides  magnificence  he  mentions  dv8paya6la, 
i.e.  manly  goodness  which  we  may  render  strenuousness. 
For  magnificence  consists  not  only  in  being  constant  in  the 
accomplishment  of  great  deeds,  which  belongs  to  constancy, 
but  also  in  bringing  a  certain  manly  prudence  and  solicitude 
to  that  accomplishment,  and  this  belongs  to  avSpayaOla, 
strenuousness:  wherefore  he  says  that  dvSpayadia  is  the 
virtue  of  a  man,  whereby  he  thinks  out  profitable  works. 


Q.  i28  THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  248 

Accordingly  it  is  evident  that  all  these  parts  may  be 
reduced  to  the  four  principal  parts  mentioned  by  Tully. 

Reply  Obj.  7.  The  five  mentioned  by  Aristotle  fall  short 
of  the  true  notion  of  virtue,  for  though  they  concur  in  the 
act  of  fortitude,  they  differ  as  to  motive,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  1,  ad  2);  wherefore  they  are  not  reckoned 
parts  but  modes  of  fortitude. 


QUESTION   CXXIX. 

OF  MAGNANIMITY.* 
(In  Eight  Articles). 

We  must  now  consider  each  of  the  parts  of  fortitude, 
including,  however,  the  other  parts  under  those  mentioned  by 
Tully,  with  the  exception  of  confidence,  for  which  we  shall 
substitute  magnanimity,  of  which  Aristotle  treats.  Accord- 
ingly we  shall  consider  (i)  Magnanimity;  (2)  Magnificence; 
(3)  Patience;  (4)  Perseverance.  As  regards  the  first  we 
shall  treat  (1)  of  magnanimity;  (2)  of  its  contrary  vices. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry: 
(1)  Whether  magnanimity  is  about  honours  ?  (2)  Whether 
magnanimity  is  only  about  great  honours  ?  (3)  Whether 
it  is  a  virtue  ?  (4)  Whether  it  is  a  special  virtue  ?  (5)  Whether 
it  is  a  part  of  fortitude  ?  (6)  Of  its  relation  to  confidence : 
(7)  Of  its  relation  to  assurance :  (8)  Of  its  relation  to  goods 
of  fortune. 

First  Article. 

whether  magnanimity  is  about  honours  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  magnanimity  is  not  about 
honours.  For  magnanimity  is  in  the  irascible  faculty,  as 
its  very  name  shows,  since  magnanimity  signifies  greatness 
of  mind,  and  mind  denotes  the  irascible  part,  as  appears 
from  De  Anima  iii.  42,  where  the  Philosopher  says  that  in 
the  sensitive  appetite  are  desire  and  mind,  i.e.  the  concupis- 
cible  and  irascible  parts.     But  honour  is  a  concupiscible 

*  Not  in  the  ordinary  restricted  sense,  but  as  explained  by  the 
author. 

249 


Q.  129.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  250 

good  since  it  is  the  reward  of  virtue.  Therefore  it  seems 
that  magnanimity  is  not  about  honours. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Sine**  magnanimity  is  a  moral  virtue,  it 
must  needs  be  about  either  passions  or  operations.  Now 
it  is  not  about  operations,  for  then  it  would  be  a  part  of 
justice:  whence  it  follows  that  it  is  about  passions.  But 
honour  is  not  a  passion.  Therefore  magnanimity  is  not 
about  honours. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  nature  of  magnanimity  seems  to 
regard  pursuit  rather  than  avoidance,  for  a  man  is  said  to  be 
magnanimous  because  he  tends  to  great  things.  But  the 
virtuous  are  praised  not  for  desiring  honours,  but  for  shun- 
ning them.     Therefore  magnanimity  is  not  about  honours. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  3)  that 
magnanimity  is  about  honour  and  dishonour. 

I  answer  that,  Magnanimity  by  its  very  name  denotes 
stretching  forth  of  the  mind  to  great  things.  Now  virtue 
bears  a  relationship  to  two  things,  first  to  the  matter  about 
which  it  is  the  field  of  its  activity,  secondly  to  its  proper  act, 
which  consists  in  the  right  use  of  such  matter.  And  since 
a  virtuous  habit  is  denominated  chiefly  from  its  act,  a  man 
is  said  to  be  magnanimous  chiefly  because  he  is  minded  to 
do  some  great  act. 

Now  an  act  may  be  called  great  in  two  ways :  in  one  way 
proportionately,  in  another  absolutely.  An  act  may  be 
called  great  proportionately,  even  if  it  consist  in  the  use  of 
some  small  or  ordinary  thing,  if,  for  instance,  one  make  a 
very  good  use  of  it:  but  an  act  is  simply  and  absolutely 
great  when  it  consists  in  the  best  use  of  the  greatest 
thing. 

The  things  which  come  into  man's  use  are  external  things, 
and  among  these  honour  is  the  greatest  simply,  both  because 
it  is  the  most  akin  to  virtue,  since  it  is  an  attestation  to  a 
person's  virtue,  as  stated  above  (Q.  OIL,  AA.  1,  2);  and 
because  it  is  offered  to  God  and  to  the  best;  and  again 
because,  in  order  to  obtain  honour  even  as  to  avoid  shame, 
men  set  aside  all  other  things.  Now  a  man  is  said  to  be 
magnanimous  in  respect  of  things  that  are  great  absolutely 


251  MAGNANIMITY  Q.  129.  Art.  i 

and  simply,  just  as  a  man  is  said  to  be  brave  in  respect  of 
things  that  are  difficult  simply.  It  follows  therefore  that 
magnanimity  is  about  honours. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Good  and  evil  absolutely  considered  regard 
the  concupiscible  faculty,  but  in  so  far  as  the  aspect  of 
difficult  is  added,  they  belong  to  the  irascible.  Thus  it  is 
that  magnanimity  regards  honour,  inasmuch,  to  wit,  as 
honour  has  the  aspect  of  something  great  or  difficult. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Although  honour  is  neither  a  passion  nor  an 
operation,  yet  it  is  the  object  of  a  passion,  namely  hope, 
which  tends  to  a  difficult  good.  Wherefore  magnanimity 
is  immediately  about  the  passions  of  hope,  and  mediately 
about  honour  as  the  object  of  hope:  even  so,  we  have  stated 
(Q.  CXXIIL,  AA.  4,  5)  with  regard  to  fortitude  that  it  is 
about  dangers  of  death  in  so  far  as  they  are  the  object  of 
fear  and  daring. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Those  are  worthy  of  praise  who  despise  riches 
in  such  a  way  as  to  do  nothing  unbecoming  in  order  to  obtain 
them,  nor  have  too  great  a  desire  for  them.  If,  however, 
one  were  to  despise  honours  so  as  not  to  care  to  do  what  is 
worthy  of  honour,  this  would  be  deserving  of  blame.  Ac- 
cordingly magnanimity  is  about  honours  in  the  sense  that 
a  man  strives  to  do  what  is  deserving  of  honour,  yet  not  so 
as  to  think  much  of  the  honour  accorded  by  man. 

Second  Article, 
whether  magnanimity  is  essentially  about  great 

HONOURS  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  magnanimity  is  not  essentially 
about  great  honours.  For  the  proper  matter  of  magna- 
nimity is  honour,  as  stated  above  (A.  1).  But  great  and  little 
are  accidental  to  honour.  Therefore  it  is  not  essential  to 
magnanimity  to  be  about  great  honours. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Just  as  magnanimity  is  about  honour, 
so  is  meekness  about  anger.  But  it  is  not  essential  to  meek- 
ness to  be  about  either  great  or  little  anger.     Therefore 


Q.  129.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  252 

neither  is  it  essential  to  magnanimity  to  be  about  great 
honour. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Small  honour  is  less  aloof  from  great 
honour  than  is  dishonour.  But  magnanimity  is  well 
ordered  in  relation  to  dishonour,  and  consequently  in  relation 
to  small  honours  also.  Therefore  it  is  not  only  about  great 
honours. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  ii.  7)  that 
magnanimity  is  about  great  honours. 

/  answer  that,  According  to  the  Philosopher  (Phys.  vii. 
17,  18),  virtue  is  a  perfection,  and  by  this  we  are  to  under- 
stand the  perfection  of  a  power,  and  that  it  regards  the 
extreme  limit  of  that  power,  as  stated  in  de  Ccelo  i.  116. 
Now  the  perfection  of  a  power  is  not  perceived  in  every 
operation  of  that  power,  but  in  such  operations  as  are  great 
or  difficult :  for  every  power,  however  imperfect,  can  extend 
to  ordinary  and  trifling  operations.  Hence  it  is  essential 
to  a  virtue  to  be  about  the  difficult  and  the  good,  as  stated 
in  Ethic,  ii.  3. 

Now  the  difficult  and  the  good  (which  amount  to  the  same) 
in  an  act  of  virtue  may  be  considered  from  two  points  of 
view.  First,  from  the  point  of  view  of  reason,  in  so  far  as  it 
is  difficult  to  find  and  establish  the  rational  means  in  some 
particular  matter:  and  this  difficulty  is  found  only  in  the 
act  of  intellectual  virtues,  and  also  of  justice.  The  other 
difficulty  is  on  the  part  of  the  matter,  which  may  involve 
a  certain  opposition  to  the  moderation  of  reason,  which 
moderation  has  to  be  applied  thereto:  and  this  difficulty 
regards  chiefly  the  other  moral  virtues,  which  are  about  the 
passions,  because  the  passions  resist  reason  as  Dionysius 
states  (Div.  Nom.  iv.  4). 

Now  as  regards  the  passions  it  is  to  be  observed  that 
the  greatness  of  this  power  of  resistance  to  reason  arises 
chiefly  in  some  cases  from  the  passions  themselves,  and  in 
others  from  the  things  that  are  the  objects  of  the  passions. 
The  passions  themselves  have  no  great  power  of  resistance, 
unless  they  be  violent,  because  the  sensitive  appetite, 
which  is  the  seat  of  the  passions,  is  naturally  subject  to 


253  MAGNANIMITY  Q.  129.  Art.  2 

reason.  Hence  the  resisting  virtues  that  are  about  these 
passions  regard  only  that  which  is  great  in  such  passions: 
thus  fortitude  is  about  very  great  fear  and  daring;  temper- 
ance about  the  concupiscence  of  the  greatest  pleasures,  and 
likewise  meekness  about  the  greatest  anger.  On  the  other 
hand,  some  passions  have  great  power  of  resistance  to  reason 
arising  from  the  external  things  themselves  that  are  the 
objects  of  those  passions :  such  are  the  love  or  desire  of  money 
or  of  honour.  And  for  these  it  is  necessary  to  have  a  virtue 
not  only  regarding  that  which  is  greatest  in  those  passions, 
but  also  about  that  which  is  ordinary  or  little:  because  things 
external,  though  they  be  little,  are  very  desirable,  as  being 
necessary  for  human  life.  Hence  with  regard  to  the  desire 
of  money  there  are  two  virtues,  one  about  ordinary  or  little 
sums  of  money,  namely  liberality,  and  another  about  large 
sums  of  money,  namely  magnificence. 

In  like  manner  there  are  two  virtues  about  honours,  one 
about  ordinarv  honours.  This  virtue  has  no  name,  but 
is  denominated  by  its  extremes,  which  are  tyiXoriixla,  i.e.  love 
of  honour,  and  a(f)i\oTi/j,la,  i.e.  without  love  of  honour:  for 
sometimes  a  man  is  commended  for  loving  honour,  and 
sometimes  for  not  caring  about  it,  in  so  far,  to  wit,  as  both 
these  things  may  be  done  in  moderation.  But  with  regard 
to  great  honours  there  is  magnanimity.  Wherefore  we 
must  conclude  that  the  proper  matter  of  magnanimity  is 
great  honour,  and  that  a  magnanimous  man  tends  to  such 
things  as  are  deserving  of  honour. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Great  and  little  are  accidental  to  honour 
considered  in  itself:  but  they  make  a  great  difference  in 
their  relation  to  reason,  the  mode  of  which  has  to  be  observed 
in  the  use  of  honour,  for  it  is  much  more  difficult  to  observe 
it  in  great  than  in  little  honours. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  In  anger  and  other  matters  only  that  which 
is  greatest  presents  any  notable  difficulty,  and  about  this 
alone  is  there  any  need  of  a  virtue.  It  is  different  with 
riches  and  honours  which  are  things  existing  outside  the 
soul. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  He  that  makes  good  use  of  great  things 


Q.  129.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  254 

is  much  more  able  to  make  good  use  of  little  things.  Ac- 
cordingly the  magnanimous  man  looks  upon  great  honours 
as  a  thing  of  which  he  is  worthy,  or  even  little  honours 
as  something  he  deserves,  because,  to  wit,  man  cannot 
sufficiently  honour  virtue  which  deserves  to  be  honoured 
by  God.  Hence  he  is  not  uplifted  by  great  honours,  because 
he  does  not  deem  them  above  him;  rather  does  he  despise 
them,  and  much  more  such  as  are  ordinary  or  little.  In  like 
manner  he  is  not  cast  down  by  dishonour,  but  despises  it, 
since  he  recognizes  that  he  does  not  deserve  it. 

Third  Article, 
whether  magnanimity  is  a  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  magnanimity  is  not  a  virtue. 
For  every  moral  virtue  observes  the  mean.  But  magna- 
nimity observes  not  the  mean  but  the  greater  extreme: 
because  the  magnanimous  man  deems  himself  worthy  of  the 
greatest  things  {Ethic,  iv.  3).  Therefore  magnanimity  is 
not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  He  that  has  one  virtue  has  them  all, 
as  stated  above  (I.-II.,  Q.  LXV.,  A.  1).  But  one  may  have  a 
virtue  without  having  magnanimity :  since  the  Philosopher 
says  (Ethic,  iv.  3)  that  whosoever  is  worthy  of  little  things 
and  deems  himself  worthy  of  them,  is  temperate,  but  he  is  not 
magnanimous.     Therefore  magnanimity  is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Virtue  is  a  good  quality  of  the  mind,  as 
stated  above  (I.-II.,  Q.  LV.,  A.  4).  But  magnanimity  implies 
certain  dispositions  of  the  body:  for  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic,  iv.  3)  of  a  magnanimous  man  that  his  gait  is  slow, 
his  voice  deep,  and  his  utterance  calm.  Therefore  magna- 
nimity is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  No  virtue  is  opposed  to  another  virtue. 
But  magnanimity  is  opposed  to  humility,  since  the  magnani- 
mous deems  himself  worthy  of  great  things,  and  despises  others, 
according  to  Ethic,  iv.  {Inc.  cit.).  Therefore  magnanimity  is 
not  a  virtue. 


255  MAGNANIMITY  Q.  129.  Art.  3 

Obj.  5.  Further,  The  properties  of  every  virtue  are  praise- 
worthy. But  magnanimity  has  certain  properties  that  call 
for  blame.  For,  in  the  first  place,  the  magnanimous  is 
unmindful  of  favours;  secondly,  he  is  remiss  and  slow  of 
action;  thirdly,  he  employs  irony*  towards  many;  fourthly, 
he  is  unable  to  associate  with  others;  fifthly,  because  he 
holds  to  the  barren  things  rather  than  to  those  that  are 
fruitful.     Therefore  magnanimity  is  not  a  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  in  praise  of  certain  men 
(2  Machab.  xv.  18):  Nicanor  hearing  of  the  valour  of  Judas' 
companions,  and  the  greatness  of  courage  (animi  magnitudi- 
nem)  with  which  they  fought  for  their  country,  was  afraid  to 
try  the  matter  by  the  sword.  Now,  only  deeds  of  virtue  are 
worthy  of  praise.  Therefore  magnanimity  which  consists 
in  greatness  of  courage  is  a  virtue. 

/  answer  that,  The  essence  of  human  virtue  consists  in 
safeguarding  the  good  of  reason  in  human  affairs,  for  this  is 
man's  proper  good.  Now  among  external  human  things 
honours  take  precedence  of  all  others,  as  stated  above 
(A.  1:  I. -II.,  Q.  11,  A.  2.,  Obj.  3).  Therefore  magnanimity, 
which  observes  the  mode  of  reason  in  great  honours,  is  a 
virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  the  Philosopher  again  says  (Ethic,  iv.  3), 
the  magnanimous  in  point  of  quantity  goes  to  extremes,  in  so 
far  as  he  tends  to  what  is  greatest,  but  in  the  matter  of  becom- 
ingness,  he  follows  the  mean,  because  he  tends  to  the  greatest 
things  according  to  reason,  for  he  deems  himself  worthy 
in  accordance  with  his  worth  (ibid.),  since  his  aims  do  not 
surpass  his  deserts. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  mutual  connexion  of  the  virtues  does 
not  apply  to  their  acts,  as  though  every  one  were  competent 
to  practise  the  acts  of  all  the  virtues.  Wherefore  the  act 
of  magnanimity  is  not  becoming  to  every  virtuous  man, 
but  only  to  great  men.  On  the  other  hand,  as  regards  the 
principles  of  virtue,  namely  prudence  and  grace,  all  virtues 
are  connected  together,  since  their  habits  reside  together 
in  the  soul,  either  in  act  or  by  way  of  a  proximate  disposition 

*  Cf.  Q.  CXI1I. 


O.  i29.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  256 

thereto.  Thus  it  is  possible  for  one  to  whom  the  act  of 
magnanimity  is  not  competent,  to  have  the  habit  of  magna- 
nimity, whereby  he  is  disposed  to  practise  that  act  if  it  were 
competent  to  him  according  to  his  state. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  movements  of  the  body  are  differen- 
tiated according  to  the  different  apprehensions  and  emotions 
of  the  soul.  And  so  it  happens  that  to  magnanimity  there 
accrue  certain  fixed  accidents  by  way  of  bodily  movements. 
For  quickness  of  movement  results  from  a  man  being  intent 
on  many  things  which  he  is  in  a  hurry  to  accomplish, 
whereas  the  magnanimous  is  intent  only  on  great  things; 
these  are  few  and  require  great  attention,  wherefore  they 
call  for  slow  movement.  Likewise  shrill  and  rapid  speaking 
is  chiefly  competent  to  those  who  are  quick  to  quarrel  about 
anything,  and  this  becomes  not  the  magnanimous  who  are 
busy  only  about  great  things.  And  just  as  these  disposi- 
tions of  bodily  movements  are  competent  to  the  magnani- 
mous man  according  to  the  mode  of  his  emotions,  so  too 
in  those  who  are  naturally  disposed  to  magnanimity  these 
conditions  are  found  naturally. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  There  is  in  man  something  great  which  he 
possesses  through  the  gift  of  God;  and  something  defective 
which  accrues  to  him  through  the  weakness  of  nature. 
Accordingly  magnanimity  makes  a  man  deem  himself 
worthy  of  great  things  in  consideration  of  the  gifts  he  holds 
from  God:  thus  if  his  soul  is  endowed  with  great  virtue, 
magnanimity  makes  him  tend  to  perfect  works  of  virtue; 
and  the  same  is  to  be  said  of  the  use  of  any  other  good,  such 
as  science  or  external  fortune.  On  the  other  hand,  humility 
makes  a  man  think  little  of  himself  in  consideration  of  his 
own  deficiency,  and  magnanimity  makes  him  despise  others 
in  so  far  as  they  fall  away  from  God's  gifts :  since  he  does  not 
think  so  much  of  others  as  to  do  anything  wrong  for  their 
sake.  Yet  humility  makes  us  honour  others  and  esteem  them 
better  than  ourselves,  in  so  far  as  we  see  some  of  God's  gifts 
in  them.  Hence  it  is  written  of  the  just  man  (Ps.  xiv.  4): 
In  his   sight  a  vile  person   is   contemned*  which  indicates 

*  Douay.  The  malignant  is  brought  to  nothing,  but  he  glorifieth,  etc. 


257  MAGNANIMITY  Q.  129.  Art.  3 

the  contempt  of  magnanimity,  but  he  honoureth  them  that 
fear  the  Lord,  which  points  to  the  reverential  bearing  of 
humility.  It  is  therefore  evident  that  magnanimity  and 
humility  are  not  contrary  to  one  another,  although  they  seem 
to  tend  in  contrary  directions,  because  they  proceed  accord- 
ing to  different  considerations. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  These  properties  in  so  far  as  they  belong  to  a 
magnanimous  man  call  not  for  blame,  but  for  very  great 
praise.  For  in  the  first  place,  when  it  is  said  that  the 
magnanimous  is  not  mindful  of  those  from  whom  he  has 
received  favours,  this  points  to  the  fact  that  he  takes  no 
pleasure  in  accepting  favours  from  others  unless  he  repay 
them  with  yet  greater  favour;  this  belongs  to  the  perfection 
of  gratitude,  in  the  act  of  which  he  wishes  to  excel,  even  as  in 
the  acts  of  other  virtues.  Again,  in  the  second  place,  it  is 
said  that  he  is  remiss  and  slow  of  action,  not  that  he  is  lacking 
in  doing  what  becomes  him,  but  because  he  does  not  busy 
himself  with  all  kinds  of  works,  but  only  with  great  works, 
such  as  are  becoming  to  him.  He  is  also  said,  in  the  third 
place,  to  employ  irony,  not  as  opposed  to  truth,  and  so  as 
either  to  say  of  himself  vile  things  that  are  not  true,  or  deny 
of  himself  great  things  that  are  true,  but  because  he  does  not 
disclose  all  his  greatness,  especially  to  the  large  number  of 
those  who  are  beneath  him,  since,  as  also  the  Philosopher  says 
(Ethic,  iv.  3),  it  belongs  to  a  magnanimous  man  to  be  great 
towards  persons  of  dignity  and  affluence,  and  unassuming 
towards  the  middle  class.  In  the  fourth  place,  it  is  said  that 
he  cannot  associate  with  others :  this  means  that  he  is  not  at 
home  with  others  than  his  friends:  because  he  altogether 
shuns  flattery  and  hypocrisy,  which  belong  to  littleness  of 
mind.  But  he  associates  with  all,  both  great  and  little, 
according  as  he  ought,  as  stated  above  (ad  1).  It  is  also  said, 
fifthly,  that  he  prefers  to  have  barren  things,  not  indeed 
any,  but  good,  i.e.  virtuous;  for  in  all  things  he  prefers  the 
virtuous  to  the  useful,  as  being  greater:  since  the  useful  is 
sought  in  order  to  supply  a  defect  which  is  inconsistent  with 
magnanimity. 

11.  ii.  4  17 


Q.  129.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  258 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  magnanimity  is  a  special  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  magnanimity  is  not  a  special 
virtue.  For  no  special  virtue  is  operative  in  every  virtue. 
But  the  Philosopher  states  {Ethic,  iv.  3)  that  whatever  is 
great  in  each  virtue  belongs  to  the  magnanimous.  Therefore 
magnanimity  is  not  a  special  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  acts  of  different  virtues  are  not 
ascribed  to  any  special  virtue.  But  the  acts  of  different 
virtues  are  ascribed  to  the  magnanimous  man.  For  it  is 
stated  in  Ethic,  iv.  (loc.  cit.)  that  it  belongs  to  the  magnanimous 
not  to  avoid  reproof  (which  is  an  act  of  prudence),  nor  to  act 
unjustly  (which  is  an  act  of  justice),  that  he  is  ready  to  do 
favours  (which  is  an  act  of  charity),  that  he  gives  his  services 
readily  (which  is  an  act  of  liberality),  that  he  is  truthful  (which 
is  an  act  of  truthfulness),  and  that  he  is  not  given  to  complain- 
ing (which  is  an  act  of  patience).  Therefore  magnanimity 
is  not  a  special  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Every  virtue  is  a  special  ornament  of 
the  soul,  according  to  the  saying  of  Isaias  (lxi.  10),  He 
hath  clothed  me  with  the  garments  of  salvation,  and  after- 
wards he  adds,  and  as  a  bride  adorned  with  her  jewels. 
But  magnanimity  is  the  ornament  of  all  the  virtues,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  iv.  Therefore  magnanimity  is  a  general 
virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  (Ethic,  ii.  7)  distinguishes 
it  from  the  other  virtues. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  2),  it  belongs 
to  a  special  virtue  to  establish  the  mode  of  reason  in  a 
determinate  matter.  Now  magnanimity  establishes  the 
mode  of  reason  in  a  determinate  matter,  namely  honours, 
as  stated  above  (AA.  1,  2) :  and  honour,  considered  in  itself, 
is  a  special  good,  and  accordingly  magnanimity  considered 
in  itself  is  a  special  virtue. 

Since,  however,  honour  is  the  reward  of  every  virtue,  as 


259  MAGNANIMITY  Q.  129.  Art.  4 

stated  above  (Q.  CIIL,  A.  1,  ad  2),  it  follows  that  by  reason 
of  its  matter  it  regards  all  the  virtues. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Magnanimity  is  not  about  any  kind  of 
honour,  but  great  honour.  Now,  as  honour  is  due  to  virtue, 
so  great  honour  is  due  to  a  great  deed  of  virtue.  Hence 
it  is  that  the  magnanimous  is  intent  on  doing  great  deeds  in 
every  virtue,  in  so  far,  to  wit,  as  he  tends  to  what  is  worthy 
of  great  honours. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Since  the  magnanimous  tends  to  great 
things,  it  follows  that  he  tends  chiefly  to  things  that  involve 
a  certain  excellence,  and  shuns  those  that  imply  defect. 
Now  it  savours  of  excellence  that  a  man  is  beneficent, 
generous  and  grateful.  Wherefore  he  shows  himself  ready 
to  perform  actions  of  this  kind,  but  not  as  acts  of  the  other 
virtues.  On  the  other  hand  it  is  a  proof  of  defect,  that  a 
man  thinks  so  much  of  certain  external  goods  or  evils, 
that  for  their  sake  he  abandons  and  gives  up  justice  or  any 
virtue  whatever.  Again,  all  concealment  of  the  truth 
indicates  a  defect,  since  it  seems  to  be  the  outcome  of  fear. 
Also  that  a  man  be  given  to  complaining  denotes  a  defect, 
because  by  so  doing  the  mind  seems  to  give  way  to  external 
evils.  Wherefore  these  and  like  things  the  magnanimous 
man  avoids  under  a  special  aspect,  inasmuch  as  they  are 
contrary  to  his  excellence  or  greatness. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Every  virtue  derives  from  its  species  a 
certain  lustre  or  adornment  which  is  proper  to  each  virtue: 
but  further  adornment  results  from  the  very  greatness  of 
a  virtuous  deed,  through  magnanimity  which  makes  all 
virtues  greater  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iv.  3. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  magnanimity  is  a  part  of  fortitude  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  magnanimity  is  not  a  part  of 
fortitude.  For  a  thing  is  not  a  part  of  itself.  But  magna- 
nimity appears  to  be  the  same  as  fortitude.  For  Seneca 
says  (De  Quat.  Virtut.):  If  magnanimity,  which  is  also  called 


Q.  129.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  260 

fortitude,  be  in  thy  soul,  thou  shalt  live  in  great  assurance: 
and  Tully  says  (De  Offic.  i.):  If  a  man  is  brave  we  expect  him 
to  be  magnanimous,  truth-loving,  and  far  removed  from  decep- 
tion.    Therefore  magnanimity  is  not  a  part  of  fortitude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  3)  says  that 
a  magnanimous  man  is  not  <pi\oKiv8vpo<;,  that  is,  a  lover  of 
danger.  But  it  belongs  to  a  brave  man  to  expose  himself 
to  danger.  Therefore  magnanimity  has  nothing  in  common 
with  fortitude  so  as  to  be  called  a  part  thereof. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Magnanimity  regards  the  great  in  things 
to  be  hoped  for,  whereas  fortitude  regards  the  great  in 
things  to  be  feared  or  dared.  But  good  is  of  more  import 
than  evil.  Therefore  magnanimity  is  a  more  important 
virtue  than  fortitude.     Therefore  it  is  not  a  part  thereof. 

On  the  contrary,  Macrobius  (De  Soma.  Scip.  i.)  and 
Andronicus  reckon  magnanimity  as  a  part  of  fortitude. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXL,  A.  3),  a 
principal  virtue  is  one  to  which  it  belongs  to  establish  a 
general  mode  of  virtue  in  a  principal  matter.  Now  one  of 
the  general  modes  of  virtue  is  firmness  of  mind,  because 
a  firm  standing  is  necessary  in  every  virtue,  according  to 
Ethic,  ii.  And  this  is  chiefly  commended  in  those  virtues 
that  tend  to  something  difficult,  in  which  it  is  most  difficult 
to  preserve  firmness.  Wherefore  the  more  difficult  it  is  to 
stand  firm  in  some  matter  of  difficulty,  the  more  principal 
is  the  virtue  which  makes  the  mind  firm  in  that  matter. 

Now  it  is  more  difficult  to  stand  firm  in  dangers  of  death, 
wherein  fortitude  confirms  the  mind,  than  in  hoping  for 
or  obtaining  the  greatest  goods,  wherein  the  mind  is  con- 
firmed by  magnanimity,  for,  as  man  loves  his  life  above  all 
things,  so  does  he  fly  from  dangers  of  death  more  than  any 
others.  Accordingly  it  is  clear  that  magnanimity  agrees 
with  fortitude  in  confirming  the  mind  about  some  difficult 
matter;  but  it  falls  short  thereof,  in  that  it  confirms  the 
mind  about  a  matter  wherein  it  is  easier  to  stand  firm. 
Hence  magnanimity  is  reckoned  a  part  of  fortitude,  because 
it  is  annexed  thereto  as  secondary  to  principal. 

Reply  Obj.   I.  As  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  v.   1,  3), 


26 1  MAGNANIMITY  Q.  129.  Art.  5 

to  lack  evil  is  looked  upon  as  a  good,  wherefore  not  to  be 
overcome  by  a  grievous  evil,  such  as  the  danger  of  death, 
is  looked  upon  as  though  it  were  the  obtaining  of  a  great 
good,  the  former  belonging  to  fortitude,  and  the  latter  to 
magnanimity:  in  this  sense  fortitude  and  magnanimity 
may  be  considered  as  identical.  Since,  however,  there  is  a 
difference  as  regards  the  difficulty  on  the  part  of  either  of 
the  aforesaid,  it  follows  that  properly  speaking  magnani- 
mity, according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  ii.  7),  is  a  distinct 
virtue  from  fortitude. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  A  man  is  said  to  love  danger  when  he 
exposes  himself  to  all  kinds  of  dangers,  which  seems  to  be 
the  mark  of  one  who  thinks  many  the  same  as  great.  This 
is  contrary  to  the  nature  of  a  magnanimous  man,  for  no 
one  seemingly  exposes  himself  to  danger  for  the  sake  of  a 
thing  that  he  does  not  deem  great.  But  for  things  that  are 
truly  great,  a  magnanimous  man  is  most  ready  to  expose 
himself  to  danger,  since  he  does  something  great  in  the  act 
of  fortitude,  even  as  in  the  acts  of  the  other  virtues.  Hence 
the  Philosopher  says  (ibid.)  that  the  magnanimous  man 
is  not  fjUfcpoKLvSwos,  i.e.  endangering  himself  for  small 
things,  but  fieyaXoKlvSwos,  i.e.  endangering  himself  for 
great  things.  And  Seneca  says  (De  Quot.  Virtut.):  Thou 
wilt  be  magnanimous  if  thou  neither  seekest  dangers  like  a 
rash  man,  nor  fear  est  them  like  a  coward.  For  nothing  makes 
the  soul  a  coward  save  the  consciousness  of  a  wicked  life. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Evil  as  such  is  to  be  avoided :  and  that  one 
has  to  withstand  it  is  accidental,  in  so  far,  to  wit,  as  one 
has  to  suffer  an  evil  in  order  to  safeguard  a  good.  But 
good  as  such  is  to  be  desired,  and  that  one  avoids  it  is  only 
accidental,  in  so  far,  to  wit,  as  it  is  deemed  to  surpass  the 
ability  of  the  one  who  desires  it.  Now  that  which  is  so 
essentially  is  always  of  more  account  than  that  which  is 
so  accidentally.  Wherefore  the  difficult  in  evil  things  is 
always  more  opposed  to  firmness  of  mind  than  the  difficult 
in  good  things.  Hence  the  virtue  of  fortitude  takes  pre- 
cedence of  the  virtue  of  magnanimity.  For  though  good 
is  simply  of  more  import  than  evil,  evil  is  of  more  import  in 
this  particular  respect. 


Q.  129.  Art.  6    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  262 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  confidence  belongs  to  magnanimity? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  confidence  does  not  belong  to 
magnanimity.  For  a  man  may  have  assurance  not  only 
in  himself,  but  also  in  another,  according  to  2  Cor.  iii.  4,  5, 
Such  confidence  we  have,  through  Christ  towards  God,  not  that 
we  are  sufficient  to  think  anything  of  ourselves,  as  of  our- 
selves. But  this  seems  inconsistent  with  the  idea  of 
magnanimity.  Therefore  confidence  does  not  belong  to 
magnanimity. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Confidence  seems  to  be  opposed  to  fear, 
according  to  Isa.  xii.  2,  /  will  deal  confidently  and  will  not 
fear.  But  to  be  without  fear  seems  more  akin  to  fortitude. 
Therefore  confidence  also  belongs  to  fortitude  rather  than 
to  magnanimity. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Reward  is  not  due  except  to  virtue. 
But  a  reward  is  due  to  confidence,  according  to  Heb.  iii.  6, 
where  it  is  said  that  we  are  the  house  of  Christ,  if  we  hold 
fast  the  confidence  and  glory  of  hope  unto  the  end.  Therefore 
confidence  is  a  virtue  distinct  from  magnanimity:  and  this 
is  confirmed  by  the  fact  that  Macrobius  condivides  it  with 
magnanimity  (De  Somn.  Scip.  L). 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  (De  Suv.  Rhet.  ii.)  seems  to  substi- 
tute confidence  for  magnanimity,  as  stated  above  in  the 
preceding  Question  (ad  6)  and  in  the  prologue  to  this. 

/  answer  that,  Confidence  takes  its  name  irom  fides  (faith) : 
and  it  belongs  to  faith  to  believe  something  and  in  somebody. 
But  confidence  belongs  to  hope,  according  to  Job  xi.  18, 
Thou  shall  have  confidence,  hope  being  set  before  thee.  Where- 
fore confidence  apparently  denotes  chiefly  that  a  man 
derives  hope  through  believing  the  word  of  one  who  promises 
to  help  him.  Since,  however,  faith  signifies  also  a  strong 
opinion,  and  since  one  may  come  to  have  a  strong  opinion 
about  something,  not  only  on  account  of  another's  state- 
ment, but  also  on  account  of  something  we  observe  in  another, 


263  MAGNANIMITY  Q.  120.  Art.  6 

it  follows  that  confidence  may  denote  the  hope  of  having 
something,  which  hope  we  conceive  through  observing 
something  either  in  oneself — for  instance,  through  observing 
that  he  is  healthy,  a  man  is  confident  that  he  will  live  long ; 
or  in  another,  for  instance,  through  observing  that  another 
is  friendly  to  him  and  powerful,  a  man  is  confident  that  he 
will  receive  help  from  him. 

Now  it  has  been  stated  above  (A.  1,  2  ad)  that  magnani- 
mity is  chiefly  about  the  hope  of  something  difficult.  Where- 
fore, since  confidence  denotes  a  certain  strength  of  hope 
arising  from  some  observation  which  gives  one  a  strong 
opinion  taat  one  will  obtain  a  certain  good,  it  follows  that 
confidence  belongs  to  magnanimity. 

Reply  Gbj.  1.  As  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  3),  it 
belongs  tc  the  magnanimous  to  need  nothing,  for  need  is  a 
mark  of  the  deficient.  But  this  is  to  be  understood  accord- 
ing to  the  mode  of  a  man,  hence  he  adds  or  scarcely  anything. 
For  it  surpasses  man  to  need  nothing  at  all.  For  every 
man  needs,  first,  the  Divine  assistance,  secondly,  even  human 
assistance,  since  man  is  naturally  a  social  animal,  for  he  is 
sufficient  by  himself  to  provide  for  his  own  life.  Accordingly, 
in  so  far  as  he  needs  others,  it  belongs  to  a  magnanimous 
man  to  have  confidence  in  others,  for  it  is  also  a  point  of 
excellence  in  a  man  that  he  should  have  at  hand  those  who 
are  able  to  be  of  service  to  him.  And  in  so  far  as  his  own 
ability  goes,  it  belongs  to  a  magnanimous  man  to  be  con- 
fident in  himself. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  stated  above  (I.-II.,  Q.  XXIII.,  A.  2: 
Q.  XL.,  A.  4),  when  we  were  treating  of  the  passions,  hope 
is  directly  opposed  to  despair,  because  the  latter  is  about 
the  same  object,  namely  good.  But  as  regards  contrariety 
of  objects  it  is  opposed  to  fear,  because  the  latter's  object 
is  evil.  Now  confidence  denotes  a  certain  strength  of  hope, 
wherefore  it  is  opposed  to  fear  even  as  hope  is.  Since, 
however,  fortitude  properly  strengthens  a  man  in  respect 
of  evil,  and  magnanimity  in  respect  of  the  obtaining  of 
good,  it  follows  that  confidence  belongs  more  properly 
to   magnanimity    than   to    fortitude.     Yet    because    hope 


Q.  i29.  Art.  7    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  264 

causes  daring,   which  belongs  to  fortitude,   it   follows  in 
consequence  that  confidence  pertains  to  fortitude. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Confidence,  as  stated  above,  denotes  a 
certain  mode  of  hope:  for  confidence  is  hope  strengthened 
by  a  strong  opinion.  Now  the  mode  applied  to  an  affection 
may  call  for  commendation  of  the  act,  so  that  it  become 
meritorious,  yet  it  is  not  this  that  draws  it  to  a  species  of 
virtue,  but  its  matter.  Hence,  properly  speaking,  confidence 
cannot  denote  a  virtue,  though  it  may  denote  the  conditions 
of  a  virtue.  For  this  reason  it  is  reckoned  among  ;he  parts 
of  fortitude,  not  as  an  annexed  virtue,  except  as  identified 
with  magnanimity  by  Tully  (loc.  cit.),  but  as  an  integral 
part,  as  stated  in  the  preceding  Question. 

Seventh  Article, 
whether  security  belongs  to  magnanimity? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  security  does  not  belong  to 
magnanimity.  For  security,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CXXVIIL, 
ad  6),  denotes  freedom  from  the  disturbance  of  fear.  But 
fortitude  does  this  most  effectively.  Wherefore  security 
is  seemingly  the  same  as  fortitude.  But  fortitude  does  not 
belong  to  magnanimity;  rather  the  reverse  is  the  case. 
Neither  therefore  does  security  belong  to  magnanimity. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Isidore  says  (Etym.  x.)  that  a  man  is 
said  to  be  secure  because  he  is  without  care.  But  this  seems 
to  be  contrary  to  virtue,  which  has  a  care  for  honourable 
things,  according  to  2  Tim.  ii.  15,  Carefully  study  to  present 
thyself  approved  unto  God.  Therefore  security  does  not 
belong  to  magnanimity,  which  does  great  things  in  all  the 
virtues. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Virtue  is  not  its  own  reward.  But 
security  is  accounted  the  reward  of  virtue,  according  to 
Job  xi.  14,  18,  //  thou  wilt  put  away  from  thee  the  iniquity 
that  is  in  thy  hand  being  buried  thou  shalt  sleep  secure.  There- 
fore security  does  not  belong  to  magnanimity  or  to  any 
other  virtue,  as  a  part  thereof. 


265  MAGNANIMITY  Q.  129.  Art.  7 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  says  (De  Offic.  i.)  under  the  heading: 
Magnanimity  consists  of  two  things,  that  it  belongs  to  mag- 
nanimity to  give  way  neither  to  a  troubled  mind,  nor  to  man, 
nor  to  fortune.  But  a  man's  security  consists  in  this. 
Therefore  security  belongs  to  magnanimity. 

/  answer  that,  As  the  Philosopher  says  (Rhet.  ii.  5),  fear 
makes  a  man  take  counsel,  because,  to  wit,  he  takes  care 
to  avoid  what  he  fears.  Now  security  takes  its  name  from 
the  removal  of  this  care,  of  which  fear  is  the  cause:  where- 
fore security  denotes  perfect  freedom  of  the  mind  from  fear, 
just  as  confidence  denotes  strength  of  hope.  Now,  as  hope 
directly  belongs  to  magnanimity,  so  fear  directly  regards 
fortitude.  Wherefore  as  confidence  belongs  immediately 
to  magnanimity,  so  security  belongs  immediately  to  for- 
titude. 

It  must  be  observed,  however,  that  as  hope  is  the  cause 
of  daring,  so  is  fear  the  cause  of  despair,  as  stated  above 
when  we  were  treating  of  the  passion  (I. -II.,  Q.  XLV.,  A.  2). 
Wherefore  as  confidence  belongs  indirectly  to  fortitude,  in 
so  far  as  it  makes  use  of  daring,  so  security  belongs  indirectly 
to  magnanimity,  in  so  far  as  it  banishes  despair. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Fortitude  is  chiefly  commended,  not  because 
it  banishes  fear,  which  belongs  to  security,  but  because  it 
denotes  a  firmness  of  mind  in  the  matter  of  the  passion. 
Wherefore  security  is  not  the  same  as  fortitude,  but  is  a 
condition  thereof. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Not  all  security  is  worthy  of  praise  but  only 
when  one  puts  care  aside,  as  one  ought,  and  in  things  when 
one  should  not  fear :  in  this  way  it  is  a  condition  of  fortitude 
and  of  magnanimity. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  There  is  in  the  virtues  a  certain  likeness 
to,  and  participation  of,  future  happiness,  as  stated  above 
(I. -II.,  Q.  V.,  AA.  3,  7).  Hence  nothing  hinders  a  certain 
security  from  being  a  condition  of  a  virtue,  although  perfect 
security  belongs  to  virtue's  reward. 


Q.  129.  Art.  8    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  266 


Eighth  Article, 
whether  goods  of  fortune  conduce  to  magnanimity? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  goods  of  fortune  do  not  conduce 
to  magnanimity.  For  according  to  Seneca  (De  Ira  i. : 
De  vita  beata  xvi. ) :  virtue  suffices  for  itself.  Now  magnanimity 
makes  every  virtue  great,  as  stated  above  (A.  4,  ad  3). 
Therefore  goods  of  fortune  do  not  conduce  to  magna- 
nimity. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  No  virtuous  man  despises  what  is  helpful 
to  him.  But  the  magnanimous  man  despises  whatever 
pertains  to  goods  of  fortune:  for  Tully  says  {De  Offic.  i.) 
under  the  heading:  Magnanimity  consists  of  two  things, 
that  a  great  soul  is  commended  for  despising  external  things. 
Therefore  a  magnanimous  man  is  not  helped  by  goods  of 
fortune. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Tully  adds  (ibid.)  that  it  belongs  to  a 
great  soul  so  to  bear  what  seems  troublesome,  as  nowise  to 
depart  from  his  natural  estate,  or  from  the  dignity  of  a  wise 
man.  And  Aristotle  says  (Ethic,  iv.  3)  that  a  magnanimous 
man  does  not  grieve  at  misfortune.  Now  troubles  and  mis- 
fortunes are  opposed  to  goods  of  fortune,  for  every  one 
grieves  at  the  loss  of  what  is  helpful  to  him.  Therefore 
external  goods  of  fortune  do  not  conduce  to  magnanimity. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  3)  that 
goods  of  fortune  seem  to  conduce  to  magnanimity. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  1),  magnanimity 
regards  two  things :  honour  as  its  matter,  and  the  accomplish- 
ment of  something  great  as  its  end.  Now  goods  of  fortune 
conduce  to  both  these  things.  For  since  honour  is  conferred 
on  the  virtuous,  not  only  by  the  wise,  but  also  by  the  multi- 
tude who  hold  these  goods  of  fortune  in  the  highest  esteem, 
the  result  is  that  they  show  greater  honour  to  those  who 
possess  goods  of  fortune.  Likewise  goods  of  fortune  are 
useful  organs  or  instruments  of  virtuous  deeds:  since  we 
can  easily  accomplish  things  by  means  of  riches,  power  and 


267  MAGNANIMITY  Q.  129.  Art.  8 

friends.  Hence  it  is  evident  that  goods  of  fortune  conduce 
to  magnanimity. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Virtue  is  said  to  be  sufficient  for  itself, 
because  it  can  be  without  even  these  external  goods;  yet 
it  needs  them  in  order  to  act  more  expeditiously. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  magnanimous  man  despises  external 
goods,  inasmuch  as  he  does  not  think  them  so  great  as  to 
be  bound  to  do  anything  unbecoming  for  their  sake.  Yet 
he  does  not  despise  them,  but  that  he  esteems  them  useful 
for  the  accomplishment  of  virtuous  deeds. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  If  a  man  does  not  think  much  of  a  thing, 
he  is  neither  very  joyful  at  obtaining  it,  nor  very  grieved 
at  losing  it.  Wherefore,  since  the  magnanimous  man  does 
not  think  much  of  external  goods,  that  is  goods  of  fortune, 
he  is  neither  much  uplifted  by  them  if  he  has  them,  nor  much 
cast  down  by  their  loss. 


QUESTION    CXXX 

OF  PRESUMPTION. 
(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  vices  opposed  to  magnanimity; 
and  in  the  first  place,  those  that  are  opposed  thereto  by 
excess.  These  are  three,  namely,  presumption,  ambition, 
and  vainglory.  Secondly,  we  shall  consider  pusillanimity 
which  is  opposed  to  it  by  way  of  deficiency.  Under  the 
first  head  there  are  two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether 
presumption  is  a  sin  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  opposed  to  magna- 
nimity by  excess  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  presumption  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  presumption  is  not  a  sin.  For 
the  Apostle  says:  Forgetting  the  things  that  are  behind,  I 
stretch  forth  (Vulg., — and  stretching  forth)  myself  to  those  that 
are  before.  But  it  seems  to  savour  of  presumption  that  one 
should  tend  to  what  is  above  oneself.  Therefore  presump- 
tion is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.   2.  Further,   The  Philosopher  says   (Ethic,   i.  7)  we 

should  not  listen  to  those  who  would  persuade  us  to  relish 

human  things  because  we  are  men,  or  mortal  things  because 

we  are  mortal,  but  we  should  relish  those  that  make  us  immortal: 

and  (Met.  i.)  that  man  should  pursue  divine  things  as  far  as 

possible.     Now  divine  and  immortal  things  are  seemingly 

far  above  man.     Since  then  presumption  consists  essentially 

26S 


269  PRESUMPTION  Q.  130.  Art.  i 

in  tending  to  what  is  above  oneself,  it  seems  that  presump- 
tion is  something  praiseworthy,  rather  than  a  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  Apostle  says  (2  Cor.  Hi.  5):  Not 
that  we  are  sufficient  to  think  anything  of  ourselves,  as  of 
ourselves.  If  then  presumption,  by  which  one  strives  at 
that  for  which  one  is  not  sufficient,  be  a  sin,  it  seems  that 
man  cannot  lawfully  even  think  of  anything  good:  which 
is  absurd.     Therefore  presumption  is  not  a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ecclus.  xxxvii.  3) :  0  wicked 
presumption,  whence  earnest  thou  ?  and  a  gloss  answers : 
From  a  creature  s  evil  will.  Now  all  that  comes  of  the  root 
of  an  evil  will  is  a  sin.     Therefore  presumption  is  a  sin. 

/  answer  that,  Since  whatever  is  according  to  nature,  is 
ordered  by  the  Divine  Reason,  which  human  reason  ought 
to  imitate,  whatever  is  done  in  accordance  with  human 
reason  in  opposition  to  the  order  established  in  general 
throughout  natural  things  is  vicious  and  sinful.  Now 
it  is  established  throughout  all  natural  things,  that  every 
action  is  commensurate  with  the  power  of  the  agent,  nor 
does  any  natural  agent  strive  to  do  what  exceeds  its 
ability.  Hence  it  is  vicious  and  sinful,  as  being  contrary 
to  the  natural  order,  that  any  one  should  assume  to  do  what 
is  above  his  power :  and  this  is  what  is  meant  by  presumption, 
as  its  very  name  shows.  Wherefore  it  is  evident  that  pre- 
sumption is  a  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Nothing  hinders  that  which  is  above  the 
active  power  of  a  natural  thing,  and  yet  not  above  the 
passive  power  of  that  same  thing:  thus  the  air  is  possessed 
of  a  passive  power  by  reason  of  which  it  can  be  so  changed 
as  to  obtain  the  action  and  movement  of  fire,  which  surpass 
the  active  power  of  air.  Thus  too  it  would  be  sinful  and 
presumptuous  for  a  man  while  in  a  state  of  imperfect  virtue 
to  attempt  the  immediate  accomplishment  of  what  belongs 
to  perfect  virtue.  But  it  is  not  presumptuous  or  sinful  for  a 
man  to  endeavour  to  advance  towards  perfect  virtue.  In 
this  way  the  Apostle  stretched  himself  forth  to  the  things 
that  were  before  him,  namely  continually  advancing  forward. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Divine  and  immortal  things  surpass  man 


Q.  130.  Art.  2     THE  ':  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  270 

according  to  the  order  of  nature.  Yet  man  is  possessed 
of  a  natural  power,  namely  the  intellect,  whereby  he  can 
be  united  to  immortal  and  Divine  things.  In  this  respect 
the  Philosopher  says  that  man  ought  to  pursue  immortal 
and  divine  things,  not  that  he  should  do  what  it  becomes 
God  to  do,  but  that  he  should  be  united  to  Him  in  intellect 
and  will. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  hi.  3),  what 
we  can  do  by  the  help  of  others  we  can  do  by  ourselves  in  a 
sense.  Hence  since  we  can  think  and  do  good  by  the  help 
of  God,  this  is  not  altogether  above  our  ability.  Hence 
it  is  not  presumptuous  for  a  man  to  attempt  the  accomplish- 
ment of  a  virtuous  deed:  but  it  would  be  presumptuous 
if  one  were  to  make  the  attempt  without  confidence  in  God's 
assistance. 

Second  Article. 

whether  presumption  is  opposed  to  magnanimity 

by  excess  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  presumption  is  not  opposed 
to  magnanimity  by  excess.  For  presumption  is  accounted 
a  species  of  the  sin  against  the  Holy  Ghost,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XIV.,  A.  2 :  Q.  XXL,  A.  1).  But  the  sin  against  the  Holy 
Ghost  is  not  opposed  to  magnanimity,  but  to  charity. 
Neither  therefore  is  presumption  opposed  to  magnanimity. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  It  belongs  to  magnanimity  that  one  should 
deem  oneself  worthy  of  great  things.  But  a  man  is  said  to 
be  presumptuous  even  if  he  deem  himself  worthy  of  small 
things,  if  they  surpass  his  ability.  Therefore  presumption 
is  not  directly  opposed  to  magnanimity. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  magnanimous  man  looks  upon 
external  goods  as  little  things.  Now  according  to  the 
Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.  3),  on  account  of  external  fortune 
the  presumptuous  disdain  and  wrong  others,  because  they 
deem  external  goods  as  something  great.  Therefore  presump- 
tion is  opposed  to  magnanimity,  not  by  excess,  but  only 
by  deficiency. 


271  PRESUMPTION  Q.  130.  Art.  2 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  ii.  7;  iv.  3) 
that  the  vain  man,  i.e.  a  vapourer  or  a  wind-bag,  which 
with  us  denotes  a  presumptuous  man,  is  opposed  to  the 
magnanimous  man  by  excess. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIX.,  A.  3,  ad.  1), 
magnanimity  observes  the  means,  not  as  regards  the  quantity 
of  that  to  which  it  tends,  but  in  proportion  to  our  own 
ability:  for  it  does  not  tend  to  anything  greater  than  is 
becoming  to  us. 

Now  the  presumptuous  man,  as  regards  that  to  which 
he  tends,  does  not  exceed  the  magnanimous,  but  sometimes 
falls  far  short  of  him:  but  he  does  exceed  in  proportion 
to  his  own  ability,  whereas  the  magnanimous  man  does  not 
exceed  his.  It  is  in  this  way  that  presumption  is  opposed 
to  magnanimity  by  excess. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  It  is  not  every  presumption  that  is  accounted 
a  sin  against  the  Holy  Ghost,  but  that  by  which  one  con- 
temns the  Divine  justice  through  inordinate  confidence 
in  the  Divine  mercy.  The  latter  kind  of  presumption,  by 
reason  of  its  matter,  inasmuch,  to  wit,  as  it  implies  con- 
tempt of  something  Divine,  is  opposed  to  charity,  or  rather 
to  the  gift  of  fear,  whereby  we  revere  God.  Nevertheless, 
in  so  far  as  this  contempt  exceeds  the  proportion  to  one's 
own  ability,  it  can  be  opposed  to  magnanimity. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Presumption,  like  magnanimity,  seems  to 
tend  to  something  great.  For  we  are  not,  as  a  rule,  wont 
to  call  a  man  presumptuous  for  going  beyond  his  powers 
in  something  small.  If,  however,  such  a  man  be  called 
presumptuous,  this  kind  of  presumption  is  not  opposed 
to  magnanimity,  but  to  that  virtue  which  is  about  ordinary 
honour,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIX.,  A.  2). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  No  one  attempts  what  is  above  his  ability, 
except  in  so  far  as  he  deems  his  ability  greater  than  it  is. 
In  this  one  may  err  in  two  ways.  First  only  as  regards 
quantity,  as  when  a  man  thinks  he  has  greater  virtue,  or 
knowledge,  or  the  like,  than  he  has.  Secondly,  as  regards 
the  kind  of  thing,  as  when  he  thinks  himself  great,  and 
worthy  of  great  things,,  by  reason  of  something  that  does 


Q.  130.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  272 

not  make  him  so,  for  instance  by  reason  of  riches  or  goods 
of  fortune.  For,  as  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  3), 
those  who  have  these  things  without  virtue,  neither  justly 
deem  themselves  worthy  of  great  things,  nor  are  rightly  called 
magnanimous. 

Again,  the  thing  to  which  a  man  sometimes  tends  in 
excess  of  his  ability,  is  sometimes  in  very  truth  something 
great,  simply  as  in  the  case  of  Peter,  whose  intent  was  to 
suffer  for  Christ,  which  has  exceeded  his  power;  while  some- 
times it  is  something  great,  not  simply,  but  only  in  the 
opinion  of  fools,  such  as  wearing  costly  clothes,  despising 
and  wronging  others.  This  savours  of  an  excess  of 
magnanimity,  not  in  any  truth,  but  in  people's  opinion. 
Hence  Seneca  says  (De  Quat.  Virtut.)  that  when  magna- 
nimity exceeds  its  measure,  it  makes  a  man  high-handed, 
proud,  haughty,  restless,  and  bent  on  excelling  in  all  things, 
whether  in  words  or  in  deeds,  without  any  considerations  of 
virtue.  Thus  it  is  evident  that  the  presumptuous  man 
sometimes  falls  short  of  the  magnanimous  in  reality,  although 
in  appearance  he  surpasses  him. 


QUESTION   CXXXI. 

OF    AMBITION. 
(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  ambition:  and  under  this  head 
there  are  two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  it  is  a  sin  ? 
(2)  Whether  it  is  opposed  to  magnanimity  by  excess  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  ambition  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  ambition  is  not  a  sin.  For 
ambition  denotes  the  desire  of  honour.  Now  honour  is 
in  itself  a  good  thing,  and  the  greatest  of  external  goods: 
wherefore  those  who  care  not  for  honour  are  reproved. 
Therefore  ambition  is  not  a  sin;  rather  is  it  something 
deserving  of  praise,  in  so  far  as  a  good  is  laudably  desired. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Anyone  may,  without  sin,  desire  what 
is  due  to  him  as  a  reward.  Now  honour  is  the  reward  of 
virtue,  as  the  Philosopher  sta.tes(  Ethic,  i.  12;  iv.  3;  viii.  14). 
Therefore  ambition  of  honour  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  That  which  heartens  a  man  to  do  good 
and  disheartens  him  from  doing  evil,  is  not  a  sin.  Now 
honour  heartens  men  to  do  good  and  to  avoid  evil;  thus 
the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.  8)  that  with  the  bravest  men, 
cowards  are  held  in  dishonour,  and  the  brave  in  honour:  and 
Tully  says  (De  Tusc.  Quczst.  i.)  that  honour  fosters  the  arts. 
Therefore  ambition  is  not  a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (1  Cor.  xiii.  5)  that  charity  is 
II.  ii.  4  273  18 


Q.  131.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  274 

not  ambitious,  seeketh  not  her  own.     Now  nothing  is  contrary 
to  charity,  except  sin.     Therefore  ambition  is  a  sin. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CIII.,  AA.  1,  2),  honour 
denotes  reverence  shown  to  a  person  in  witness  of  his  ex- 
cellence. Now  two  things  have  to  be  considered  with 
regard  to  man's  honour.  The  first  is  that  a  man  has  not 
from  himself  the  thing  in  which  he  excels,  for  this  is,  as  it 
were,  something  Divine  in  him,  wherefore  on  this  count 
honour  is  due  principally,  not  to  him  but  to  God.  The 
second  point  that  calls  for  observation  is  that  the  thing  in 
which  man  excels  is  given  to  him  by  God,  that  he  may 
profit  others  thereby:  wherefore  a  man  ought  so  far  to  be 
pleased  that  others  bear  witness  to  his  excellence,  as  this 
enables  him  to  profit  others. 

Now  the  desire  of  honour  may  be  inordinate  in  three 
ways.  First,  when  a  man  desires  recognition  of  an  excel- 
lence which  he  has  not :  this  is  to  desire  more  than  his  share 
of  honour.  Secondly,  when  a  man  desires  honour  for  him- 
self without  referring  it  to  God.  Thirdly,  when  a  man's 
appetite  rests  in  honour  itself,  without  referring  it  to  the 
profit  of  others.  Since  then  ambition  denotes  inordinate 
desire  of  honour,  it  is  evident  that  it  is  always  a  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  desire  for  good  should  be  regulated 
according  to  reason,  and  if  it  exceed  this  rule  it  will  be 
sinful.  In  this  way  it  is  sinful  to  desire  honour  in  disaccord 
with  the  order  of  reason.  Now  those  are  reproved  who 
care  not  for  honour  in  accordance  with  reason's  dictate  that 
they  should  avoid  what  is  contrary  to  honour. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Honour  is  not  the  reward  of  virtue,  as 
regards  the  virtuous  man,  in  this  sense  that  he  should  seek 
for  it  as  his  reward :  since  the  reward  he  seeks  is  happiness, 
which  is  the  end  of  virtue.  But  it  is  said  to  be  the  reward 
of  virtue  as  regards  others,  who  have  nothing  greater  than 
honour  whereby  to  reward  the  virtuous;  which  honour 
deceives  greatness  from  the  very  fact  that  it  bears  witness 
to  virtue.  Hence  it  is  evident  that  it  is  not  an  adequate 
reward,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iv.  3. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Just  as  some  are  heartened  to  do  good  and 


275  AMBITION  Q.  131.  Art.  2 

disheartened  from  doing  evil,  by  the  desire  of  honour, 
if  this  be  desired  in  due  measure;  so,  if  it  be  desired  inordin- 
ately, it  may  become  to  man  an  occasion  of  doing  many 
evil  things,  as  when  a  man  cares  not  by  what  means  he 
obtains  honour.  Wherefore  Sallust  says  (Catilin.)  that 
the  good  as  well  as  the  wicked  covet  honours  for  themselves,  but 
the  one,  i.e.  the  good,  go  about  it  in  the  right  way,  whereas 
the  other,  i.e.  the  wicked,  through  lack  of  the  good  acts,  make 
use  of  deceit  and  falsehood.  Yet  they  who,  merely  for  the 
sake  of  honour,  either  do  good  or  avoid  evil,  are  not  virtuous, 
according  to  the  Philosopher  [Ethic,  iii.  8),  where  he  says 
that  they  who  do  brave  things  for  the  sake  of  honour  are 
not  truly  brave. 

Second  Article. 

whether  ambition  is  opposed  to  magnanimity 

by  excess  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  ambition  is  not  opposed  to 
magnanimity  by  excess.  For  one  mean  has  only  one 
extreme  opposed  to  it  on  the  one  side.  Now  presumption 
is  opposed  to  magnanimity  by  excess  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXXX.,  A.  2).  Therefore  ambition  is  not  opposed  to 
it  by  excess. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Magnanimity  is  about  honours;  whereas 
ambition  seems  to  regard  positions  of  dignity:  for  it  is 
written  (2  Machab.  iv.  7)  that  Jason  ambitiously  sought 
the  high  priesthood.  Therefore  ambition  is  not  opposed  to 
magnanimity. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Ambition  seems  to  regard  outward  show: 
for  it  is  written  (Acts  xxv.  27)  that  Agrippa  and  Berenice 
.  .  .  with  great  pomp  (ambitione)  .  .  .  had  entered  into  the 
hall  of  audience*  and  (2  Para.  xvi.  14)  that  when  Asa  died 
they  burnt  spices  and  .  .  .  ointments  over  his  body  with  very 
great  pomp   [ambitione).     But    magnanimity  is  not   about 

*  Praetorium.  The  Vulgate  has  auditorium,  but  the  meaning  is 
the  same. 


Q.  131.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  276 

outward   show.      Therefore    ambition   is   not    opposed  to 
magnanimity. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  says  (De  Offic.  i.)  that  the  more  a 
man  exceeds  in  magnanimity,  the  more  he  desires  himself 
alone  to  dominate  others.  But  this  pertains  to  ambition. 
Therefore  ambition  denotes  an  excess  of  magnanimity. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  1),  ambition  signifies 
inordinate  love  of  honour.  Now  magnanimity  is  about 
honours  and  makes  use  of  them  in  a  becoming  manner. 
Wherefore  it  is  evident  that  ambition  is  opposed  to  magna- 
nimity as  the  inordinate  to  that  which  is  well  ordered. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Magnanimity  regards  two  things.  It 
regards  one  as  its  end,  in  so  far  as  it  is  some  great  deed  that 
the  magnanimous  man  attempts  in  proportion  to  his  ability. 
In  this  way  presumption  is  opposed  to  magnanimity  by 
excess:  because  the  presumptuous  man  attempts  great 
deeds  beyond  his  ability.  The  other  thing  that  magnani- 
mity regards  is  its  matter,  viz.  honour,  of  which  it  makes 
right  use:  and  in  this  way  ambition  is  opposed  to  magna- 
nimity by  excess.  Nor  is  it  impossible  for  one  mean  to  be 
exceeded  in  various  respects. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Honour  is  due  to  those  who  are  in  a  position 
of  dignity,  on  account  of  a  certain  excellence  of  their  estate : 
and  accordingly  inordinate  desire  for  positions  of  dignit}' 
pertains  to  ambition.  For  if  a  man  were  to  have  an  inor- 
dinate desire  for  a  position  of  dignity,  not  for  the  sake  of 
honour,  but  for  the  sake  of  a  right  use  of  a  dignity  exceeding 
his  ability,  he  would  not  be  ambitious  but  presumptuous. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  very  solemnity  of  outward  worship 
is  a  kind  of  honour,  wherefore  in  such  cases  honour  is  wont 
to  be  shown.  This  is  signified  by  the  words  of  James 
(ii.  2,  3):  If  there  shall  come  into  your  assembly  a  man  having 
a  golden  ring,  in  fine  apparel,  .  .  .  and  you  .  .  .  shall  say  to 
him:  Sit  thou  here  well,  etc.  Wherefore  ambition  does  not 
regard  outward  worship,  except  in  so  far  as  this  is  a  kind  of 
honour. 


QUESTION  CXXXII. 

OF    VAINGLORY. 

(In  Five  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  vainglory:  under  which  head  there 
are  five  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  desire  of  glory  is  a 
sin  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  opposed  to  magnanimity  ?  (3)  Whether 
t  is  a  mortal  sin  ?  (4)  Whether  it  is  a  capital  vice  ?  (5)  Of 
its  daughters. 

First  Article, 
whether  the  desire  of  glory  is  a  sin  ? 

We  Proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  desire  of  glory  is  not  a  sin. 
For  no  one  sins  in  being  likened  to  God :  in  fact  we  are  com- 
manded (Eph.  v.  L):  Be  ye  .  .  .  followers  of  God,  as  most 
dear  children.  Now  by  seeking  glory  man  seems  to  imitate 
God,  Who  seeks  glory  from  men:  wherefore  it  is  written 
(Isa.  xliii.  6,  7):  Bring  My  sons  from  afar,  and  My  daughters 
from  the  ends  of  the  earth.  A  nd  every  one  that  calleth  on  My 
name,  I  have  created  him  for  My  glory.  Therefore  the  desire 
for  glory  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  That  which  incites  a  man  to  do  good  is 
apparently  not  a  sin.  Now  the  desire  of  glory  incites  men 
to  do  good.  For  Tully  says  (De  Tusc.  Qucest.  i.)  that  glory 
inflames  every  man  to  strive  his  utmost :  and  in  Holy  Writ 
glory  is  promised  for  good  works,  according  to  Rom.  ii.  7  : 
To  them,  indeed,  who  according  to  patience  in  good  work  .  .  . 
glory  and  honour*   Therefore  the  desire  for  glory  is  not  a  sin. 

*  Vulg., — Who  will  render  to  every  man  according  to  his  works,  to 
them  indeed  who  .  .  .  seek  glory  and  honour  and  incorruption,  eternal 
life. 

2  77 


Q.  132.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  278 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Tully  says  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  glory 
is  consistent  good  report  about  a  person,  together  with  praise  : 
and  this  comes  to  the  same  as  what  Augustine  says  (Contra 
Maximin.  iii.),  viz.  that  glory  is,  as  it  were,  clear  knowledge 
with  praise.  Now  it  is  no  sin  to  desire  praiseworthy  renown : 
indeed,  it  seems  itself  to  call  for  praise,  according  to 
Ecclus.  xli.  15,  Take  care  of  a  good  name,  and  Rom.  xii.  17, 
Providing  good  things  not  only  in  the  sight  of  God,  but  also  in 
the  sight  of  all  men.  Therefore  the  desire  of  vainglory  is 
not  a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  v.):  He  is 
better  advised  who  acknowledges  that  even  the  love  of  praise 
is  sinful. 

I  answer  that,  Glory  signifies  a  certain  charity,  wherefore 
Augustine  says  (Tract,  lxxxii.,  c,  cxiv.  in  Joan.)  that  to 
be  glorified  is  the  same  as  to  be  clarified.  Now  clarity  and 
comeliness  imply  a  certain  display:  wherefore  the  word 
glory  properly  denotes  the  display  of  something  as  regards 
its  seeming  comely  in  the  sight  of  men,  whether  it  be  a 
bodily  or  a  spiritual  good.  Since,  however,  that  which  is 
clear  simply  can  be  seen  by  many,  and  by  those  who  are 
far  away,  it  follows  that  the  word  glory  properly  denotes 
that  somebody's  good  is  known  and  approved  by  many, 
according  to  the  saying  of  Sallust  (Catilin.):*  I  must  not 
boast  while  I  am  addressing  one  man. 

But  if  we  take  the  word  glory  in  a  broader  sense,  it  not 
only  consists  in  the  knowledge  of  many,  but  also  in  the 
knowledge  of  few,  or  of  one,  or  of  oneself  alone,  as  when  one 
considers  one's  own  good  as  being  worthy  of  praise.  Now 
it  is  not  a  sin  to  know  and  approve  one's  own  good:  for  it 
is  written  (1  Cor.  ii.  12):  Now  we  have  received  not  the  spirit 
of  this  world,  but  the  Spirit  that  is  of  God,  that  we  may  know 
the  things  that  are  given  us  from  God.  Likewise  it  is  not  a  sin 
to  be  willing  to  approve  one's  own  good  works:  for  it  is 
written  (Matth.  v.  16):  Let  your  light  shine  before  men. 
Hence  the  desire  for  glory  does  not,  of  itself,  denote  a  sin: 
but  the  desire  for  empty  or  vain  glory  denotes  a  sin:  for  it 
*  The  quotation  is  from  Livy  (Hist.,  Lib.  XXII.,  C.  39). 


279  OF  VAINGLORY  Q.  132.  Art.  i 

is  sinful  to  desire  anything  vain,  according  to  Ps.  iv.  3,  Why 
do  you  love  vanity,  and  seek  after  lying  ? 

Now  glory  may  be  called  vain  in  three  ways.  First,  on 
the  part  of  the  thing  for  which  one  seeks  glory:  as  when  a 
man  seeks  glory  for  that  which  is  unworthy  of  glory,  for 
instance  when  he  seeks  it  for  something  frail  and  perishable: 
secondly,  on  the  part  of  him  from  whom  he  seeks  glory, 
for  instance  a  man  whose  judgment  is  uncertain:  thirdly, 
on  the  part  of  the  man  himself  who  seeks  glory,  for  that  he 
does  not  refer  the  desire  of  his  own  glory  to  a  due  end,  such 
as  God's  honour,  or  the  spiritual  welfare  of  his  neighbour. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  Augustine  says  on  John  xiii.  13,  You  call 
Me  Master  and  Lord  ;  and  you  say  well  (Tract,  lviii.  in  Joan.) : 
Self-complacency  is  fraught  with  danger  of  one  who  has  to 
beware  of  pride.  But  He  Who  is  above  all,  however  much  He 
may  praise  Himself,  does  not  uplift  Himself.  For  knowledge 
of  God  is  our  need,  not  His  :  nor  does  any  man  know  Him 
unless  he  be  taught  of  Him  Who  knows.  It  is  therefore 
evident  that  God  seeks  glory,  not  for  His  own  sake,  but  for 
ours.  In  like  manner  a  man  may  rightly  seek  his  own 
glory  for  the  good  of  others,  according  to  Matth.  v.  16,  That 
they  may  see  your  good  works,  and  glorify  your  Father  Who  is 
in  heaven. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  That  which  we  receive  from  God  is  not  vain 
but  true  glory:  it  is  this  glory  that  is  promised  as  a  reward 
for  good  works,  and  of  which  it  is  written  (2  Cor.  x.  17,  18): 
He  that  glorieth  let  him  glory  in  the  Lord,  for  not  he  who 
commendeth  himself  is  approved,  but  he  whom  God  com- 
mendeth.  It  is  true  that  some  are  heartened  to  do  works  of 
virtue,  through  desire  for  human  glory,  as  also  through  the 
desire  for  other  earthly  goods.  Yet  he  is  not  truly  virtuous 
who  does  virtuous  deeds  for  the  sake  of  human  glory,  as 
Augustine  proves  (De  Civ.  Dei  v.). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  It  is  requisite  for  man's  perfection  that  he 
should  know  himself;  but  not  that  he  should  be  known  by 
others,  wherefore  it  is  not  to  be  desired  in  itself.  It  may, 
however,  be  desired  as  being  useful  for  something,  either 
in  order  that  God  may  be  glorified  by  men,  or  that  men  may 


Q.  132.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  280 

become  better  by  reason  of  the  good  they  know  to  be  in 
another  man,  or  in  order  that  man,  knowing  by  the  testi- 
mony of  others'  praise  the  good  which  is  in  him,  may  himself 
strive  to  persevere  therein  and  to  become  better.  In  this 
sense  it  is  praiseworthy  that  a  man  should  take  care  of  his 
good  name,  and  that  he  should  provide  good  things  in  the 
sight  of  God  and  men  :  but  not  that  he  should  take  an  empty 
pleasure  in  human  praise. 

Second  Article, 
whether  vainglory  is  opposed  to  magnanimity  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  vainglory  is  not  opposed  to 
magnanimity.  For,  as  stated  above  (Ai),  vainglory  consists 
in  glorying  in  things  that  are  not,  which  pertains  to  false- 
hood; or  in  earthly  and  perishable  things,  which  pertains  to 
covetousness;  or  in  the  testimony  of  men,  whose  judgment 
is  uncertain,  which  pertains  to  imprudence.  Now  these 
vices  are  not  contrary  to  magnanimity.  Therefore  vain- 
glory is  not  opposed  to  magnanimity. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Vainglory  is  not,  like  pusillanimity, 
opposed  to  magnanimity  by  way  of  deficiency,  for  this  seems 
inconsistent  with  vainglory.  Nor  is  it  opposed  to  it  by  way 
of  excess,  for  in  this  way  presumption  and  ambition  are 
opposed  to  magnanimity,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CXXX.,  A.  2: 
Q.  CXXXL,  A.  2) :  and  these  differ  from  vainglory.  There- 
fore vainglory  is  not  opposed  to  magnanimity. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  A  gloss  on  Philip,  ii.  3,  Let  nothing  be 
done  through  contention,  neither  by  vainglory,  says:  Some 
among  them  were  given  to  dissension  and  restlessness,  con- 
tending with  one  another  for  the  sake  of  vainglory.  But 
contention*  is  not  opposed  to  magnanimity.  Neither 
therefore  is  vainglory. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  says  (De  Offic.  i.)  under  the  heading, 
Magnanimity  consists  in  two  things  :  We  should  beware  of 
the  desire  for  glory,  since  it  enslaves  the  mind,  which  a  mag- 

*  Cf.  Q.  XXXVIII. 


28 1  OF  VAINGLORY  Q.  132.  Art.  2 

nanimous    man   should   ever   strive   to   keep    untrammelled. 
Therefore  it  is  opposed  to  magnanimity. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CIIL,  A.  1,  ad  3),  glory 
is  an  effect  of  honour  and  praise:  because  from  the  fact  that 
a  man  is  praised,  or  shown  any  kind  of  reverence,  he  acquires 
charity  in  the  knowledge  of  others.  And  since  magnanimity 
is  about  honour,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIX.,  AA.  1,  2), 
it  follows  that  it  also  is  about  glory:  seeing  that  as  a  man 
uses  honour  moderately,  so  too  does  he  use  glory  in  modera- 
tion. Wherefore  inordinate  desire  of  glory  is  directly 
opposed  to  magnanimity. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  To  think  so  much  of  little  things  as  to  glory 
in  them  is  itself  opposed  to  magnanimity.  Wherefore  it 
is  said  of  the  magnanimous  man  (Ethic,  iv.)  that  honour  is 
of  little  account  to  him.  In  like  manner  he  thinks  little  of 
other  things  that  are  sought  for  honour's  sake,  such  as  power 
and  wealth.  Likewise  it  is  inconsistent  with  magnanimity 
to  glory  in  things  that  are  not;  wherefore  it  is  said  of  the 
magnanimous  man  (Ethic,  iv.)  that  he  cares  more  for  truth 
than  for  opinion.  Again  it  is  incompatible  with  magnani- 
mity for  a  man  to  glory  in  the  testimony  of  human  praise, 
as  though  he  deemed  this  something  great;  wherefore  it  is 
said  of  the  magnanimous  man  (Ethic,  iv.,  loc.  cit.),  that  he 
cares  not  to  be  praised.  And  so,  when  a  man  looks  upon 
little  things  as  though  they  were  great,  nothing  hinders  this 
from  being  contrary  to  magnanimity,  as  well  as  to  other 
virtues. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  He  that  is  desirous  of  vainglory  does  in 
truth  fall  short  of  being  magnanimous,  because  he  glories  in 
what  the  magnanimous  man  thinks  little  of,  as  stated  in  the 
preceding  Reply.  But  if  we  consider  his  estimate,  he  is- 
opposed  to  the  magnanimous  man  by  way  of  excess,  because 
the  glory  which  he  seeks  is  something  great  in  his  estimation, 
and  he  tends  thereto  in  excess  of  his  deserts. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXVIL,  A.  2,  ad  2), 
the  opposition  of  vices  does  not  depend  on  their  effects. 
Nevertheless  contention,  if  done  intentionally,  is  opposed  to 
magnanimity:   since   no   one  contends  save   for   what   he 


Q.  132.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  282 

deems  great.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  3) 
that  the  magnanimous  man  is  not  contentious,  because 
nothing  is  great  in  his  estimation. 


Third  Article, 
whether  vainglory  is  a  mortal  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  vainglory  is  a  mortal  sin. 
For  nothing  precludes  the  eternal  reward  except  a  mortal 
sin.  Now  vainglory  precludes  the  eternal  reward :  for  it  is 
written  (Matth.  vi.  1) :  Take  heed,  that  you  do  not  give  justice 
before  men,  to  be  seen  by  them :  otherwise  you  shall  not  have  a 
reward  of  your  Father  Who  is  in  heaven.  Therefore  vainglory 
is  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Whoever  appropriates  to  himself  that 
which  is  proper  to  God,  sins  mortally.  Now  by  desiring 
vainglory,  a  man  appropriates  to  himself  that  which  is 
proper  to  God.  For  it  is  written  (Isa.  xlii.  8) :  /  will  not  give 
My  glory  to  another,  and  (1  Tim.  i.  17) :  To  ...  the  only 
God  be  honour  and  glory.    Therefore  vainglory  is  a  mortal  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Apparently  a  sin  is  mortal  if  it  be  most 
dangerous  and  harmful.  Now  vainglory  is  a  sin  of  this 
kind,  because  a  gloss  of  Augustine  on  1  Thess.  ii.  4,  God, 
Who  proveth  our  hearts,  says :  Unless  a  man  war  against  the 
love  of  human  glory  he  does  not  perceive  its  baneful  power, 
for  though  it  be  easy  for  anyone  not  to  desire  praise  as  long  as 
one  does  not  get  it,  it  is  difficult  not  to  take  pleasure  in  it,  when 
it  is  given.  Chrysostom  also  says  (Horn.  xix.  in  Matth.) 
that  vainglory  enters  secretly,  and  robs  us  insensibly  of  all 
our  inward  possessions.  Therefore  vainglory  is  a  mortal 
sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Chrysostom  says*  that  while  other  vices 
find  their  abode  in  the  servants  of  the  devil,  vainglory  finds 
a  place  even  in  the  servants  of  Christ.  Yet  in  the  latter  there 
is  no  mortal  sin.     Therefore  vainglory  is  not  a  mortal  sin. 

*  Horn.  xiii.  in  the  Opus  Imperfectum  falsely  ascribed  to  S.  John 
Chrysostom. 


283  OF  VAINGLORY  Q.  132.  Art.  3 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXIV..  A.  12:  Q.  CX., 
A.  4:  Q.  CXIL,  A.  2),  a  sin  is  mortal  through  being  contrary 
to  charity.  Now  the  sin  of  vainglory,  considered  in  itself, 
does  not  seem  to  be  contrary  to  charity  as  regards  the  love 
of  one's  neighbour:  yet  as  regards  the  love  of  God  it  may 
be  contrary  to  charity  in  two  ways.  In  one  way,  by  reason 
of  the  matter  about  which  one  glories:  for  instance  when 
one  glories  in  something  false  that  is  opposed  to  the  reverence 
we  owe  God,  according  to  Ezech.  xxviii.  2,  Thy  heart  is 
lifted  up,  and  Thou  hast  said:  I  am  God,  and  1  Cor.  iv.  7, 
What  hast  thou  that  thou  hast  not  received?  And  if  thou  hast 
received,  why  dost  thou  glory,  as  if  thou  hadst  not  received  it  ? 
Or  again  when  a  man  prefers  to  God  the  temporal  good  in 
which  he  glories:  for  this  is  forbidden  (Jerem.  ix.  23,  24): 
Let  not  the  wise  man  glory  in  his  wisdom,  and  let  not  the 
strong  man  glory  in  his  strength,  and  let  not  the  rich  man 
glory  in  his  riches.  But  let  him  that  glorieth  glory  in  this, 
that  he  understandeth  and  knoweth  Me,  Or  again  when  a  man 
prefers  the  testimony  of  man  to  God's;  thus  it  is  written  in 
reproval  of  certain  people  (John  xii.  43) :  For  they  loved  the 
glory  of  men  more  than  the  glory  of  God. 

In  another  way  vainglory  may  be  contrary  to  charity, 
on  the  part  of  the  one  who  glories,  in  that  he  refers  his 
intention  to  glory  as  his  last  end:  so  that  he  directs  even 
virtuous  deeds  thereto,  and,  in  order  to  obtain  it,  forbears 
not  from  doing  even  that  which  is  against  God.  In  this 
way  it  is  a  mortal  sin.  Wherefore  Augustine  says  (De 
Civ.  Dei  v.  14)  that  this  vice,  namely  the  love  of  human 
praise,  is  so  hostile  to  a  godly  faith,  if  the  heart  desires  glory 
more  than  it  fears  or  loves  God,  that  Our  Lord  said  (John  v.  44) : 
How  can  you  believe,  who  receive  glory  one  from  another, 
and  the  glory  which  is  from  God  alone,  you  do  not  seek  ? 

If,  however,  the  love  of  human  glory,  though  it  be  vain, 
be  not  inconsistent  with  charity,  neither  as  regards  the 
matter  gloried  in,  nor  as  to  the  intention  of  him  that  seeks 
glory,  it  is  not  a  mortal  but  a  venial  sin. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  No  man,  by  sinning,  merits  eternal  life: 
wherefore  a  virtuous  deed  loses  its  power  to  merit  eternal 


Q.  132.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  284 

life,  if  it  be  done  for  the  sake  of  vainglory,  even  though 
that  vainglory  be  not  a  mortal  sin.  On  the  other  hand  when 
a  man  loses  the  eternal  reward  simply  through  vainglory, 
and  not  merely  in  respect  of  one  act,  vainglory  is  a  mortal 
sin. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Not  every  man  that  is  desirous  of  vainglory, 
desires  the  excellence  which  belongs  to  God  alone.  For 
the  glory  due  to  God  alone  differs  from  the  glory  due  to  a 
virtuous  or  rich  man. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Vainglory  is  stated  to  be  a  dangerous  sin, 
not  only  on  account  of  its  gravity,  but  also  because  it  is  a 
disposition  to  grave  sins,  in  so  far  as  it  renders  man  presump- 
tuous and  too  self-confident :  and  so  it  gradually  disposes  a 
man  to  lose  his  inward  goods. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  vainglory  is  a  capital  vice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  vainglory  is  not  a  capital  sin. 
For  a  vice  that  always  arises  from  another  vice  is  seemingly 
not  capital.  But  vainglory  always  arises  from  pride. 
Therefore  vainglory  is  not  a  capital  vice. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Honour  would  seem  to  take  precedence 
of  glory,  for  this  is  its  effect.  Now  ambition  which  is  inor- 
dinate desire  of  honour  is  not  a  capital  vice.  Neither 
therefore  is  the  desire  of  vainglory. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  A  capital  vice  has  a  certain  prominence. 
But  vainglory  seems  to  have  no  prominence,  neither  as  a 
sin,  because  it  is  not  always  a  mortal  sin,  nor  considered  as 
an  appetible  good,  since  human  glory  is  apparently  a  frail 
thing,  and  is  something  outside  man  himself.  Therefore 
vainglory  is  not  a  capital  vice. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  [Moral,  xxxi.)  numbers  vain- 
glory among  the  seven  capital  vices. 

I  answer  that,  The  capital  vices  are  enumerated  in  two 
ways.  For  some  reckon  pride  as  one  of  their  number: 
and  these  do  not  place  vainglory  among  the  capital  vices. 


285  OF  VAINGLORY  Q.  132.  Art.  4 

Gregory,  however  (Moral,  xxxi.),  reckons  pride  to  be  the 
queen  of  all  the  vices,  and  vainglory,  which  is  the  immediate 
offspring  of  pride,  he  reckons  to  be  a  capital  vice :  and  not 
without  reason.  For  pride,  as  we  shall  state  farther  on 
(0.  CLIL,  AA.  1,  2),  denotes  inordinate  desire  of  excellence. 
But  whatever  good  one  may  desire,  one  desires  a  certain 
perfection  and  excellence  therefrom:  wherefore  the  end  of 
every  vice  is  directed  to  the  end  of  pride,  so  that  this  vice 
seems  to  exercise  a  kind  of  causality  over  the  other  vices, 
and  ought  not  to  be  reckoned  among  the  special  sources  of 
vice,  known  as  the  capital  vices.  Now  among  the  goods 
that  are  the  means  whereby  man  acquires  honour,  glory 
seems  to  be  the  most  conducive  to  that  effect,  inasmuch 
as  it  denotes  the  manifestation  of  a  man's  goodness:  since 
good  is  naturally  loved  and  honoured  by  all.  Wherefore, 
just  as  by  the  glory  which  is  in  God's  sight  man  acquires 
honour  in  Divine  things,  so  too  by  the  glory  which  is  in 
the  sight  of  man  he  acquires  excellence  in  human  things. 
Hence  on  account  of  its  close  connexion  with  excellence, 
which  men  desire  above  all,  it  follows  that  it  is  most  desirable. 
And  since  many  vices  arise  from  the  inordinate  desire 
thereof,  it  follows  that  vainglory  is  a  capital  vice. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  It  is  not  impossible  for  a  capital  vice  to 
arise  from  pride,  since  as  stated  above  (in  the  body  of  the 
Article  and  I. -II.,  Q.  LXXXIV.,  A.  2)  pride  is  the  queen 
and  mother  of  all  the  vices. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Praise  and  honour,  as  stated  above  (A.  2), 
stand  in  relation  to  glory  as  the  causes  from  which  it  pro- 
ceeds, so  that  glory  is  compared  to  them  as  their  end.  For 
the  reason  why  a  man  loves  to  be  honoured  and  praised 
is  that  he  thinks  thereby  to  acquire  a  certain  renown  in  the 
knowledge  of  others. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Vainglory  stands  prominent  under  the 
aspect  of  desirability,  for  the  reason  given  above,  and  this 
suffices  for  it  to  be  reckoned  a  capital  vice.  Nor  is  it  always 
necessary  for  a  capital  vice  to  be  a  mortal  sin;  for  mortal 
sin  can  arise  from  venial  sin,  inasmuch  as  venial  sin  can 
dispose  man  thereto. 


Q.132.ART.5     THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  286 


Fifth  Article. 

whether  the  daughters  of  vainglory  are  suitably 
reckoned  to  be  disobedience,  boastfulness, 
hypocrisy,  contention,  obstinacy,  discord,  and 
love  of  novelties  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article: — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  daughters  of  vainglory 
are  unsuitably  reckoned  to  be  disobedience,  boastfulness, 
hypocrisy,  contention,  obstinacy,  discord,  and  eccentricity* 
For  according  to  Gregory  (Moral,  xxiii.)  boastfulness  is 
numbered  among  the  species  of  pride.  Now  pride  does  not 
arise  from  vainglory,  rather  is  it  the  other  way  about,  as 
Gregory  says  (Moral,  xxxi.).  Therefore  boastfulness  should 
not  be  reckoned  among  the  daughters  of  vainglory. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Contention  and  discord  seem  to  be  the 
outcome  chiefly  of  anger.  But  anger  is  a  capital  vice 
condivided  with  vainglory.  Therefore  it  seems  that  they 
are  not  the  daughters  of  vainglory. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Chrysostom  says  (Horn.  xix.  in  Matth.) 
that  vainglory  is  always  evil,  but  especially  in  philan- 
thropy, i.e.  mercy.  And  yet  this  is  nothing  new,  for  it 
is  an  established  custom  among  men.  Therefore  eccen- 
tricity should  not  be  specially  reckoned  as  a  daughter  of 
vainglory. 

On  the  contrary  stands  the  authority  of  Gregory  (Moral. 
xxxi.),  who  there  assigns  the  above  daughters  to  vainglory. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXXIV.,  A.  5: 
Q.  XXXV.,  A.  4:  I.-IL,  0.  LXXXIV.,  AA.  3,  4),  the  vices 
which  by  their  very  nature  are  such  as  to  be  directed  to  the 
end  of  a  certain  capital  vice,  are  called  its  daughters.  Now 
the  end  of  vainglory  is  the  manifestation  of  one's  own 
excellence,  as  stated  above  (AA.  1,  4) :  and  to  this  end  a 
man  may  tend  in  two  ways.  In  one  way  directly,  either  by 
words,  and  this  is  boasting,  or  by  deeds,  and  then  if  they 
be  true  and  call  for   astonishment,  it   is  love  of  novelties 

*  Praesumptio  novitatum,  literally  presumption  of  novelties. 


287  OF  VAINGLORY  Q.  132.  Art.  5 

which  men  are  wont  to  wonder  at  most;  but  if  they  be  false, 
it  is  hypocrisy.  In  another  way  a  man  strives  to  make 
known  his  excellence  by  showing  that  he  is  not  inferior  to 
another,  and  this  in  four  ways.  First,  as  regards  the 
intellect,  and  thus  we  have  obstinacy,  by  which  a  man  is 
too  much  attached  to  his  own  opinion,  being  unwilling  to 
believe  one  that  is  better.  Secondly,  as  regards  the  will, 
and  then  we  have  discord,  whereby  a  man  is  unwilling  to 
give  up  his  own  will,  and  agree  with  others.  Thirdly,  as 
regards  speech,  and  then  we  have  contention,  whereby  a  man 
quarrels  noisily  with  another.  Fourthly,  as  regards  deeds, 
and  this  is  disobedience,  whereby  a  man  refuses  to  carry 
out  the  command  of  his  superiors. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXII.,  AA.  1,  2), 
boasting  is  reckoned  a  kind  of  pride,  as  regards  its  interior 
cause,  which  is  arrogance:  but  outward  boasting,  according 
to  Ethic,  iv.,  is  directed  sometimes  to  gain,  but  more  often 
to  glory  and  honour,  and  thus  it  is  the  result  of  vainglory. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Anger  is  not  the  cause  of  discord  and  con- 
tention, except  in  conjunction  with  vainglory,  in  that  a 
man  thinks  it  a  glorious  thing  for  him  not  to  yield  to  the 
will  and  words  of  others. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Vainglory  is  reproved  in  connexion  with 
almsdeeds  on  account  of  the  lack  of  charity  apparent  in 
one  who  prefers  vainglory  to  the  good  of  his  neighbour, 
seeing  that  he  does  the  latter  for  the  sake  of  the  former. 
But  a  man  is  not  reproved  for  presuming  to  give  alms  as 
though  this  were  something  novel. 


QUESTION    CXXXIII. 

OF  PUSILLANIMITY. 

(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  pusillanimity.  Under  this  head 
there  are  two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  pusillanimity 
is  a  sin  ?   (2)  To  what  virtue  is  it  opposed  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  pusillanimity  is  a  sin  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  pusillanimity  is  not  a  sin.  For 
every  sin  makes  a  man  evil,  just  as  every  virtue  makes  a 
man  good.  But  a  fainthearted  man  is  not  evil,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  3).  Therefore  pusillanimity  is 
not  a  sin. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  Philosopher  says  [ibid.)  that  a 
fainthearted  man  is  especially  one  who  is  worthy  of  great 
goods,  yet  does  not  deem  hi7nself  worthy  of  them.  Now  no  one 
is  worthy  of  great  goods  except  the  virtuous,  since  as  the 
Philosopher  again  says  {ibid.),  none  but  the  virtuous  are 
truly  worthy  of  honour.  Therefore  the  fainthearted  are 
virtuous :  and  consequently  pusillanimity  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Pride  is  the  beginning  of  all  sin  (Ecclus. 
x.  15).  But  pusillanimity  does  not  proceed  from  pride, 
since  the  proud  man  sets  himself  above  what  he  is,  while 
the  fainthearted  man  withdraws  from  the  things  he  is 
worthy  of.     Therefore  pusillanimity  is  not  a  sin. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  3)  that 
he  who  deems  himself  less  worthy  than  he  is,  is  said  to  befaint- 

288 


289  PUSILLANIMITY  Q.  133-  Art  1. 

hearted.  Now  sometimes  holy  men  deem  themselves  less 
worthy  than  they  are;  for  instance,  Moses  and  Elias,  who 
were  worthy  of  the  office  God  chose  them  for,  which  they 
both  humbly  declined  (Exod.  iii.  n:  Jerem.  i.  6).  There- 
fore pusillanimity  is  not  a  sin. 

On  the  contrary,  Nothing  in  human  conduct  is  to  be 
avoided  save  sin.  Now  pusillanimity  is  to  be  avoided: 
for  it  is  written  (Coloss.  iii.  21):  Fathers,  provoke  not  your 
children  to  indignation,  lest  they  be  discouraged.  Therefore 
pusillanimity  is  a  sin. 

/  answer  that,  Whatever  is  contrary  to  a  natural  inclina- 
tion is  a  sin,  because  it  is  contrary  to  a  law  of  nature. 
Now  everything  has  a  natural  inclination  to  accomplish  an 
action  that  is  commensurate  with  its  power :  as  is  evident 
in  all  natural  things,  whether  animate  or  inanimate.  Now 
just  as  presumption  makes  a  man  exceed  what  is  propor- 
tionate to  his  power,  by  striving  to  do  more  than  he  can,  so 
pusillanimity  makes  a  man  fall  short  of  what  is  proportionate 
to  his  power,  by  refusing  to  tend  to  that  which  is  commen- 
surate thereto.  Wherefore  as  presumption  is  a  sin,  so  is 
pusillanimity.  Hence  it  is  that  the  servant  who  buried  in 
the  earth  the  money  he  had  received  from  his  master,  and 
did  not  trade  with  it  through  fainthearted  fear,  was  punished 
by  his  master  (Matth.  xxv. ;  Luke  xix.). 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  Philosopher  calls  those  evil  who  injure 
their  neighbour:  and  accordingly  the  fainthearted  is  said 
not  to  be  evil,  because  he  injures  no  one,  save  accidentally, 
by  omitting  to  do  what  might  be  profitable  to  others.  For 
Gregory  says  (Pastoral,  i.)  that  if  they  who  demur  to  do  good 
to  their  neighbour  in  preaching  be  judged  strictly,  without 
doubt  their  guilt  is  proportionate  to  the  good  they  might  have 
done  had  they  been  less  retiring. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Nothing  hinders  a  person  who  has  a  virtuous 
habit  from  sinning  venially  and  without  losing  the  habit, 
or  mortally  and  with  loss  of  the  habit  of  gratuitous  virtue. 
Hence  it  is  possible  for  a  man,  by  reason  of  the  virtue  which 
he  has,  to  be  worthy  of  doing  certain  great  things  that  are 
worthy  of  great  honour,  and  yet  through  not  trying  to  make 

11.  ii.  4  19 


Q.  133.  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  290 

use  of  his  virtue,  he  sins  sometimes  venially,  sometimes 
mortally. 

Again  it  may  be  replied  that  the  fainthearted  is  worthy 
of  great  things  in  proportion  to  his  ability  for  virtue,  ability 
which  he  derives  either  from  a  good  natural  disposition,  or 
from  science,  or  from  external  fortune,  and  if  he  fails  to  use 
those  things  for  virtue,  he  becomes  guilty  of  pusillanimity. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Even  pusillanimity  may  in  some  way  be 
the  result  of  pride:  when,  to  wit,  a  man  clings  too  much  to 
his  own  opinion,  whereby  he  thinks  himself  incompetent 
for  those  things  for  which  he  is  competent.  Hence  it  is 
written  (Prov.  xxvi.  16):  The  sluggard  is  wiser  in  his  own 
conceit  than  seven  men  that  speak  sentences.  For  nothing 
hinders  him  from  depreciating  himself  in  some  things,  and 
having  a  high  opinion  of  himself  in  others.  Wherefore 
Gregory  says  {Pastor,  i.)  of  Moses  that  perchance  he  would 
have  been  proud,  had  he  undertaken  the  leadership  of  a 
numerous  people  without  misgiving:  and  again  he  would  have 
been  proud,  had  he  refused  to  obey  the  command  of  his 
Creator. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Moses  and  Jeremias  were  worthy  of  the 
office  to  which  they  were  appointed  by  God,  but  their  worthi- 
ness was  of  Divine  grace:  yet  they,  considering  the  insuffi- 
ciency of  their  own  weakness,  demurred;  though  not  obsti- 
nately lest  they  should  fall  into  pride. 

Second  Article, 
whether  pusillanimity  is  opposed  to  magnanimity  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  pusillanimity  is  not  opposed  to 
magnanimity.  For  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  3)  that 
the  fainthearted  man  knows  not  himself :  for  he  would  desire 
the  good  things,  of  which  he  is  worthy,  if  he  knew  himself. 
Now  ignorance  of  self  seems  opposed  to  prudence.  There- 
fore pusillanimity  is  opposed  to  prudence. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Our  Lord  calls  the  servant  wicked  and 
slothful  who  through  pusillanimity  refused  to   make  use 


2gi  PUSILLANIMITY  Q.  133-  Art.  2 

of  the  money.  Moreover  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv., 
loc.  cit.)  that  the  fainthearted  seem  to  be  slothful.  Now 
sloth  is  opposed  to  solicitude,  which  is  an  act  of  prudence, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XLVIL,  A.  9).  Therefore  pusillanimity 
is  not  opposed  to  magnanimity. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Pusillanimity  seems  to  proceed  from 
inordinate  fear :  hence  it  is  written  (Isa.  xxxv.  4) :  Say  to  the 
fainthearted :  Take  courage  and  fear  not.  It  also  seems  to 
proceed  from  inordinate  anger,  according  to  Coloss.  iii.  21, 
Fathers,  provoke  not  your  children  to  indignation,  lest  they  be 
discouraged.  Now  inordinate  fear  is  opposed  to  fortitude, 
and  inordinate  anger  to  meekness.  Therefore  pusillanimity 
is  not  opposed  to  magnanimity. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  The  vice  that  is  in  opposition  to  a  par- 
ticular virtue  is  the  more  grievous  according  as  it  is  more 
unlike  that  virtue.  Now  pusillanimity  is  more  unlike 
magnanimity  than  presumption  is.  Therefore  if  pusillani- 
mity is  opposed  to  magnanimity,  it  follows  that  it  is  a  more 
grievous  sin  than  presumption:  yet  this  is  contrary  to  the 
saying  of  Ecclus.  xxxvii.  3,  0  wicked  presumption,  whence 
earnest  thou  ?  Therefore  pusillanimity  is  not  opposed  to 
magnanimity. 

On  the  contrary,  Pusillanimity  and  magnanimity  differ 
as  greatness  and  littleness  of  soul,  as  their  very  names 
denote.  Now  great  and  little  are  opposites.  Therefore 
pusillanimity  is  opposed  to  magnanimity. 

i"  answer  that,  Pusillanimity  may  be  considered  in  three 
ways.  First,  in  itself;  and  thus  it  is  evident  that  by  its 
very  nature  it  is  opposed  to  magnanimity,  from  which  it 
differs  as  great  and  little  differ  in  connexion  with  the  same 
subject.  For  just  as  the  magnanimous  man  tends  to  great 
things  out  of  greatness  of  soul,  so  the  pusillanimous  man 
shrinks  from  great  things  out  of  littleness  of  soul.  Secondly, 
it  may  be  considered  in  reference  to  its  cause,  which  on  the 
part  of  the  intellect  is  ignorance  of  one's  own  qualification, 
and  on  the  part  of  the  appetite  is  the  fear  of  failure  in  what 
one  falsely  deems  to  exceed  one's  ability.  Thirdly,  it  may  be 
considered  in  reference  to  its  effect,  which  is  to  shrink  from 


O. 133.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  292 

the  great  things  of  which  one  is  worthy.  But,  as  stated 
above  (0.  CXXXIL,  A.  2,  ad  3),  opposition  between  vice 
and  virtue  depends  rather  on  their  respective  species  than 
on  their  cause  or  effect.  Hence  pusillanimity  is  directly 
opposed  to  magnanimity 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  argument  considers  pusillanimity  as 
proceeding  from  a  cause  in  the  intellect.  Yet  it  cannot 
be  said  properly  that  it  is  opposed  to  prudence,  even  in 
respect  of  its  cause :  because  ignorance  of  this  kind  does  not 
proceed  from  indiscretion  but  from  laziness  in  considering 
one's  own  ability,  according  to  Ethic,  iv.  3,  or  in  accomplish- 
ing what  is  within  one's  power. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  argument  considers  pusillanimity  from 
the  point  of  view  of  its  effect. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  This  argument  considers  the  point  of  view 
of  cause.  Nor  is  the  fear  that  causes  pusillanimity  always 
a  fear  of  the  dangers  of  death :  wherefore  it  does  not 
follow  from  this  standpoint  that  pusillanimity  is  opposed  to 
fortitude.  As  regards  anger,  if  we  consider  it  under  the 
aspect  of  its  proper  movement,  whereby  a  man  is  roused  to 
take  vengeance,  it  does  not  cause  pusillanimity,  which  dis- 
heartens the  soul;  on  the  contrary,  it  takes  it  away.  If, 
however,  we  consider  the  causes  of  anger,  which  are  injuries 
inflicted  whereby  the  soul  of  the  man  who  suffers  them  is 
disheartened,  it  conduces  to  pusillanimity. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  According  to  its  proper  species  pusillanimity 
is  a  graver  sin  than  presumption,  since  thereby  a  man  with- 
draws from  good  things,  which  is  a  very  great  evil  according 
to  Ethic,  iv.  Presumption,  however,  is  stated  to  be  wicked 
on  account  of  pride  whence  it  proceeds. 


QUESTION  CXXXIV. 

OF  MAGNIFICENCE. 
(In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  magnificence  and  the  vices  opposed 
to  it.  With  regard  to  magnificence  there  are  four  points  of 
inquiry :  (i)  Whether  magnificence  is  a  virtue  ?  (2)  Whether 
it  is  a  special  virtue  ?  (3)  What  is  its  matter  ?  (4)  Whether 
it  is  a  part  of  fortitude  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  magnificence  is  a  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  magnificence  is  not  a  virtue. 
For  whoever  has  one  virtue  has  all  the  virtues,  as  stated 
above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXV.,  A.  1).  But  one  may  have  the  other 
virtues  without  having  magnificence:  because  the  Philo- 
sopher says  {Ethic,  iv.  2)  that  not  every  liberal  man  is  magni- 
ficent.    Therefore  magnificence  is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Moral  virtue  observes  the  mean,  accord- 
ing to  Ethic,  ii.  6.  But  magnificence  does  not  seemingly 
observe  the  mean,  for  it  exceeds  liberality  in  greatness. 
Now  great  and  little  are  opposed  to  one  another  as  extremes, 
the  mean  of  which  is  equal,  as  stated  in  Met.  x.  Hence 
magnificence  observes  not  the  mean,  but  the  extreme. 
Therefore  it  is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  No  virtue  is  opposed  to  a  natural  inclina- 
tion, but  on  the  contrary  perfects  it,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CVIII.,  A.  2:  Q.  CXVII.,  A.  1,  Obj.  1).  Now  according 
to  the  Philosopher  [Ethic,  iv.  2)  the  magnificent  man  is  not 

293 


Q.  i34-  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  294 

lavish  towards  himself :  and  this  is  opposed  to  the  natural 
inclination  one  has  to  look  after  oneself.  Therefore  magni- 
ficence is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  According  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  vi.  4) 
act  is  right  reason  about  things  to  be  made.  Now  magnificence 
is  about  things  to  be  made,  as  its  very  name  denotes.* 
Therefore  it  is  an  act  rather  than  a  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  Human  virtue  is  a  participation  of  Divine 
power.  But  magnificence  [virtutis)  belongs  to  Divine 
power,  according  to  Ps.  lxvii.  35:  His  magnificence  and 
His  power  is  in  the  clouds.  Therefore  magnificence  is  a 
virtue. 

/  answer  that,  According  to  De  Ccelo  i.  16,  we  speak  of 
virtue  in  relation  to  the  extreme  limit  of  a  thing  s  power,  not 
as  regards  the  limit  of  deficiency,  but  as  regards  the  limit 
of  excess,  the  very  nature  of  which  denotes  something  great. 
Wherefore  to  do  something  great,  whence  magnificence 
takes  its  name,  belongs  properly  to  the  very  notion  of  virtue. 
Hence  magnificence  denotes  a  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Not  every  liberal  man  is  magnificent  as 
regards  his  actions,  because  he  lacks  the  wherewithal  to 
perform  magnificent  deeds.  Nevertheless  every  liberal 
man  has  the  habit  of  magnificence,  either  actually  or  in 
respect  of  a  proximate  disposition  thereto,  as  explained 
above  (Q.  CXXIX.,  A.  3,  ad  2),  as  also  (I.-II.,  Q.  LXV.,  A.  1) 
when  we  were  treating  of  the  connexion  of  virtues. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  is  true  that  magnificence  observes  the 
extreme,  if  we  consider  the  quantity  of  the  thing  done :  yet 
it  observes  the  mean,  if  we  consider  the  rule  of  reason,  which 
it  neither  falls  short  of  nor  exceeds,  as  we  have  also  said  of 
magnanimity  (Q.  CXXIX.,  A.  3,  ad  1). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  It  belongs  to  magnificence  to  do  something 
great.  But  that  which  regards  a  man's  person  is  little  in 
comparison  with  that  which  regards  Divine  things,  or  even 
the  affairs  of  the  community  at  large.  Wherefore  the 
magnificent  man  does  not  intend  principally  to  be  lavish 
towards  himself,  not  that  he  does  not  seek  his  own  good,  but 

*  Magnificence  =  magna  facere — i.e.  to  make  great  things. 


295  MAGNIFICENCE  Q.  134-  Art.  2 

because  to  do  so  is  not  something  great.  Yet  if  anything 
regarding  himself  admits  of  greatness,  the  magnificent  man 
accomplishes  it  magnificently:  for  instance,  things  that  are 
done  once,  such  as  a  wedding,  or  the  like;  or  things  that  are 
of  a  lasting  nature;  thus  it  belongs  to  a  magnificent  man  to 
provide  himself  with  a  suitable  dwelling,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iv. 
Reply  Obj.  4.  As  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vi.  5)  there 
must  needs  be  a  virtue  of  act,  i.e.  a  moral  virtue,  whereby  the 
appetite  is  inclined  to  make  good  use  of  the  rule  of  act :  and 
this  is  what  magnificence  does.  Hence  it  is  not  an  act  but 
a  virtue. 

Second  Article, 
whether  magnificence  is  a  special  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  magnificence  is  not  a  special 
virtue.  For  magnificence  would  seem  to  consist  in  doing 
something  great.  But  it  may  belong  to  any  virtue  to  do 
something  great,  if  the  virtue  be  great :  as  in  the  case  of  one 
who  has  a  great  virtue  of  temperance,  for  he  does  a  great 
work  of  temperance.  Therefore,  magnificence  is  not  a 
special  virtue,  but  denotes  a  perfect  degree  of  any  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Seemingly  that  which  tends  to  a  thing 
is  the  same  as  that  which  does  it.  But  it  belongs  to  mag- 
nanimity to  tend  to  something  great,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXXIX.,  AA.  1,  2).  Therefore  it  belongs  to  magna- 
nimity likewise  to  do  something  great.  Therefore  magnifi- 
cence is  not  a  special  virtue  distinct  from  magnanimity. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Magnificence  seems  to  belong  to  holiness, 
for  it  is  written  (Exod.  xv.  n) :  Magnificent  (Douay, — 
Glorious)  in  holiness,  and  (Ps.  xcv.  6) :  Holiness  and  magni- 
ficence (Douay, — Majesty)  in  His  sanctuary.  Now  holiness 
is  the  same  as  religion,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXXL,  A.  8). 
Therefore  magnificence  is  apparently  the  same  as  religion. 
Therefore  it  is  not  a  special  virtue,  distinct  from  the  others. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  reckons  it  with  other 
special  virtues  (Ethic,  ii.  7;  iv.  2). 

I  answer  that,  It  belongs  to  magnificence  to  do  (facere) 


Q.  134.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  296 

something  great,  as  its  name  implies.  Now  facer e  may  be 
taken  in  two  ways,  in  a  strict  sense,  and  in  a  broad  sense. 
Strictly  facer e  means  to  work  something  in  external  matter, 
for  instance  to  make  a  house,  or  something  of  the  kind;  in 
a  broad  sense  facere  is  employed  to  denote  any  action, 
whether  it  passes  into  external  matter,  as  to  burn  or  cut, 
or  remain  in  the  agent,  as  to  understand  or  will. 

Accordingly  if  magnificence  be  taken  to  denote  the  doing 
of  something  great,  the  doing  {f actio)  being  understood  in 
the  strict  sense,  it  is  then  a  special  virtue.  For  the  work  done 
is  produced  by  act:  in  the  use  of  which  it  is  possible  to 
consider  a  special  aspect  of  goodness,  namely  that  the  work 
produced  (factum)  by  the  act  is  something  great,  namely  in 
quantity,  value,  or  dignity,  and  this  is  what  magnificence 
does.     In  this  way  magnificence  is  a  special  virtue. 

If,  on  the  other  hand,  magnificence  take  its  name  from 
doing  something  great,  the  doing  (facere)  being  understood 
in  a  broad  sense,  it  is  not  a  special  virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1  It  belongs  to  every  perfect  virtue  to  do 
something  great  in  the  genus  of  that  virtue,  if  doing  (facere) 
be  taken  in  the  broad  sense,  but  not  if  it  be  taken  strictly, 
for  this  is  proper  to  magnificence. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  belongs  to  magnanimity  not  only  to  tend 
to  something  great,  but  also  to  do  great  works  in  all  the 
virtues,  either  by  making  (faciendo),  or  by  any  kind  of 
action,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iv.  3 :  yet  so  that  magnanimity,  in 
this  respect,  regards  the  sole  aspect  of  great,  while  the  other 
virtues  which,  if  they  be  perfect,  do  something  great,  direct 
their  principal  intention,  not  to  something  great,  but  to  that 
which  is  proper  to  each  virtue :  and  the  greatness  of  the  thing 
done  is  sometimes  consequent  upon  the  greatness  of  the 
virtue. 

On  the  other  hand,  it  belongs  to  magnificence  not  only  to 
do  something  great,  doing  (facere)  being  taken  in  the  strict 
sense,  but  also  to  tend  with  the  mind  to  the  doing  of  great 
things.  Hence  Tully  says  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  magni- 
ficence is  the  discussing  and  administering  of  great  and  lofty 
undertakings,  with  a  certain  broad  and  noble  purpose  of  mind, 


297  MAGNIFICENCE  Q.i34Art.3 

discussion  referring  to  the  inward  intention,  and  adminis- 
tration to  the  outward  accomplishment.  Wherefore  just 
as  magnanimity  intends  something  great  in  every  matter, 
it  follows  that  magnificence  does  the  same  in  every  work  that 
can  be  produced  in  external  matter  (factibili). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  intention  of  magnificence  is  the  produc- 
tion of  a  great  work.  Now  works  done  by  men  are  directed 
to  an  end:  and  no  end  of  human  works  is  so  great  as  the 
honour  of  God:  wherefore  magnificence  does  a  great  work 
especially  in  reference  to  the  Divine  honour.  Wherefore  the 
Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  2)  that  the  most  commendable 
expenditure  is  that  which  is  directed  to  Divine  sacrifices:  and 
this  is  the  chief  object  of  magnificence.  For  this  reason 
magnificence  is  connected  with  holiness,  since  its  chief 
effect  is  directed  to  religion  or  holiness. 

Third  Article. 

whether  the  matter  of  magnificence  is  great 

expenditure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  matter  of  magnificence  is 
not  great  expenditure.  For  there  are  not  two  virtues  about 
the  same  matter.  But  liberality  is  about  expenditure,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  CXVII.,  A.  2).  Therefore  magnificence 
is  not  about  expenditure. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Every  magnificent  man  is  liberal  (Ethic. 
iv.  2).  But  liberality  is  about  gifts  rather  than  about 
expenditure.  Therefore  magnificence  also  is  not  chiefly 
about  expenditure,  but  about  gifts. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  belongs  to  magnificence  to  produce 
an  external  work.  But  not  even  great  expenditure  is 
always  the  means  of  producing  an  external  work,  for  instance 
when  one  spends  much  in  sending  presents.  Therefore 
expenditure  is  not  the  proper  matter  of  magnificence. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  Only  the  rich  are  capable  of  great  expen- 
diture. But  the  poor  are  able  to  possess  all  the  virtues, 
since  the  virtues  do  not  necessarily  require  external  fortune, 


Q.  i34.  Art  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  298 

but  are  sufficient  for  themselves,  as  Seneca  says  {De  Ira  i. : 
De  vita  beata  xvi.).  Therefore  magnificence  is  not  about 
great  expenditure. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.  2)  that 
magnificence  does  not  extend,  like  liberality,  to  all  transactions 
in  money,  but  only  to  expensive  ones,  wherein  it  exceeds 
liberality  in  scale.  Therefore  it  is  only  about  great  expen- 
diture. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  2),  it  belongs  to  mag- 
nificence to  intend  doing  some  great  work.  Now  for  the 
doing  of  a  great  work,  proportionate  expenditure  is  necessary, 
for  great  works  cannot  be  produced  without  great  expendi- 
ture. Hence  it  belongs  to  magnificence  to  spend  much  in 
order  that  some  great  work  may  be  accomplished  in  becoming 
manner.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  loc.  cit. ) 
that  a  magnificent  man  will  produce  a  more  magnificent  work 
with  equal,  i.e.  proportionate,  expenditure.  Now  expendi- 
ture is  the  outlay  of  a  sum  of  money;  and  a  man  may  be 
hindered  from  making  that  outlay  if  he  love  money  too 
much.  Hence  the  matter  of  magnificence  may  be  said  to 
be  both  this  expenditure  itself,  which  the  magnificent  man 
uses  to  produce  a  great  work,  and  also  the  very  money 
which  he  employs  in  going  to  great  expense,  and  as  well  as 
the  love  of  money,  which  love  the  magnificent  man  mode- 
rates, lest  he  be  hindered  from  spending  much. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIX.,  A.  2),  those 
virtues  that  are  about  external  things  experience  a  certain 
difficulty  arising  from  the  genus  itself  of  the  thing  about 
which  the  virtue  is  concerned,  and  another  difficulty  besides 
arising  from  the  greatness  of  that  same  thing.  Hence  the 
need  for  two  virtues,  concerned  about  money  and  its  use; 
namely,  liberality,  which  regards  the  use  of  money  in  general, 
and  magnificence,  which  regards  that  which  is  great  in  the 
use  of  money. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  use  of  money  regards  the  liberal  man 
in  one  way  and  the  magnificent  man  in  another.  For  it 
regards  the  liberal  man,  inasmuch  as  it  proceeds  from  an 
ordinate  affection  in  respect  of  money;  wherefore  all  due 


299  MAGNIFICENCE  Q.  134-  Art.  3 

use  of  money  (such  as  gifts  and  expenditure),  the  obstacles 
to  which  are  removed  by  a  moderate  love  of  money,  belongs 
to  liberality.  But  the  use  of  money  regards  the  magnificent 
man  in  relation  to  some  great  work  which  has  to  be  produced, 
and  this  use  is  impossible  without  expenditure  or  outlay. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  magnificent  man  also  makes  gifts  of 
presents,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iv.  2,  but  not  under  the  aspect 
of  gift,  but  rather  under  the  aspect  of  expenditure  directed 
to  the  production  of  some  work,  for  instance  in  order  to 
honour  someone,  or  in  order  to  do  something  which  will 
reflect  honour  on  the  whole  state:  as  when  he  brings  to 
effect  what  the  whole  state  is  striving  for. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  The  chief  act  of  virtue  is  the  inward  choice, 
and  a  virtue  may  have  this  without  outward  fortune:  so 
that  even  a  poor  man  may  be  magnificent.  But  goods  of 
fortune  are  requisite  as  instruments  to  the  external  acts  of 
virtue:  and  in  this  way  a  poor  man  cannot  accomplish  the 
outward  act  of  magnificence  in  things  that  are  great  simply. 
Perhaps,  however,  he  may  be  able  to  do  so  in  things  that  are 
great  by  comparison  to  some  particular  work;  which,  though 
little  in  itself,  can  nevertheless  be  done  magnificently  in 
proportion  to  its  genus:  for  little  and  great  are  relative 
terms,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (De  Prcedic.  Cap.  Ad  aliquid). 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  magnificence  is  a  part  of  fortitude  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  magnificence  is  not  a  part  of 
fortitude.  For  magnificence  agrees  in  matter  with  liberality, 
as  stated  above  (A.  3).  But  liberality  is  a  part,  not  of 
fortitude,  but  of  justice.  Therefore  magnificence  is  not  a 
part  of  fortitude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Fortitude  is  about  fear  and  darings. 
But  magnificence  seems  to  have  nothing  to  do  with  fear, 
but  only  with  expenditure,  which  is  a  kind  of  action.  There- 
fore magnificence  seems  to  pertain  to  justice,  which  is  about 
actions,  rather  than  to  fortitude. 


Q.  134.  Art.  4    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  300 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  2)  that 
the  magnificent  man  is  like  the  man  of  science.  Now  science 
has  more  in  common  with  prudence  than  with  fortitude. 
Therefore  magnificence  should  not  be  reckoned  a  part  of 
fortitude. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  and  Macrobius 
{De  Somn.  Scip.  i.)  and  Andronicus  reckon  magnificence 
to  be  a  part  of  fortitude. 

/  answer  that,  Magnificence,  in  so  far  as  it  is  a  special 
virtue,  cannot  be  reckoned  a  subjective  part  of  fortitude, 
since  it  does  not  agree  with  this  virtue  in  the  point  of  matter : 
but  it  is  reckoned  a  part  thereof,  as  being  annexed  to  it  as 
secondary  to  principal  virtue. 

In  order  for  a  virtue  to  be  annexed  to  a  principal  virtue, 
two  things  are  necessary,  as  stated  above  (Q.  LXXX.). 
The  one  is  that  the  secondary  virtue  agree  with  the  prin- 
cipal, and  the  other  is  that  in  some  respect  it  be  exceeded 
thereby.  Now  magnificence  agrees  with  fortitude  in  the 
point  that  as  fortitude  tends  to  something  arduous  and 
difficult,  so  also  does  magnificence:  wherefore  seemingly  it 
is  seated,  like  fortitude,  in  the  irascible.  Yet  magnificence 
falls  short  of  fortitude,  in  that  the  arduous  thing  to  which 
fortitude  tends  derives  its  difficulty  from  a  danger  that 
threatens  the  person,  whereas  the  arduous  thing  to  which 
magnificence  tends  derives  its  difficulty  from  the  disposses- 
sion of  one's  property,  which  is  of  much  less  account  than 
danger  to  one's  person.  Wherefore  magnificence  is  accounted 
a  part  of  fortitude. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Justice  regards  operations  in  themselves, 
as  viewed  under  the  aspect  of  something  due :  but  liberality 
and  magnificence  regard  sumptuary  operations  as  related 
to  the  passions  of  the  soul,  albeit  in  different  ways.  For 
liberality  regards  expenditure  in  reference  to  the  love  and 
desire  of  money,  which  are  passions  of  the  concupiscible 
faculty,  and  do  not  hinder  the  liberal  man  from  giving  and 
spending:  so  that  this  virtue  is  in  the  concupiscible.  On 
the  other  hand,  magnificence  regards  expenditure  in  refer- 
ence to  hope,  by  attaining  to  the  difficulty,  not  simply,  as 


301  MAGNIFICENCE  Q.  134.  Art.  4 

magnanimity  does,  but  in  a  determinate  matter,  namely 
expenditure:  wherefore  magnificence,  like  magnanimity,  is 
apparently  in  the  irascible  part. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Although  magnificence  does  not  agree  with 
fortitude  in  matter,  it  agrees  with  it  as  to  the  condition  of 
its  matter :  since  it  tends  to  something  difficult  in  the  matter 
of  expenditure,  even  as  fortitude  tends  to  something  difficult 
in  the  matter  of  fear. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Magnificence  directs  the  use  of  art  to  some- 
thing great,  as  stated  above  and  in  the  preceding  Article. 
Now  art  is  in  the  reason.  Wherefore  it  belongs  to  the  mag- 
nificent man  to  use  his  reason  by  observing  proportion  of 
expenditure  to  the  work  he  has  in  hand.  This  is  especially 
necessary  on  account  of  the  greatness  of  both  those  things, 
since  if  he  did  not  take  careful  thought,  he  would  incur  the 
risk  of  a  great  loss. 


QUESTION  CXXXV. 

OF   MEANNESS.* 
(In  Two  Articles). 

We  must  now  consider  the  vices  opposed  to  magnificence: 
under  which  head  there  are  two  points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether 
meanness  is  a  vice  ?     (2)  Of  the  vice  opposed  to  it. 

First  Article 
whether  meanness  is  a  vice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  meanness  is  not  a  vice.  For 
just  as  vice  moderates  great  things,  so  does  it  moderate 
little  things :  wherefore  both  the  liberal  and  the  magnificent 
do  little  things.  But  magnificence  is  a  virtue.  Therefore 
likewise  meanness  is  a  virtue  rather  than  a  vice. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.  2)  that 
careful  reckoning  is  mean.  But  careful  reckoning  is  appa- 
rently praiseworthy,  since  man's  good  is  to  be  in  accordance 
with  reason,  as  Dionysius  states  (Div.  Nom.  iv.  4).  There- 
fore meanness  is  not  a  vice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  iv.  2)  that 
a  mean  man  is  loth  to  spend  money.  But  this  belongs  to 
covetousness  or  illiberality.  Therefore  meanness  is  not  a 
distinct  vice  from  the  others. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  (Ethic,  ii.)  accounts 
meanness  a  special  vice  opposed  to  magnificence. 

/    answer   that,    As   stated    above    (I. -II.,   Q.  I.,  A.   3: 

*  Parviftcentia,  or  doing  mean  things,  just  as  magnificentia  is 
doing  great  things. 

302 


303  MEANNESS  Q.  135.  Art.  i 

Q.  XVIII.,  A.  6),  moral  acts  take  their  species  from  their 
end,  wherefore  in  many  cases  they  are  denominated  from 
that  end.  Accordingly  a  man  is  said  to  be  mean  [parvificus ) 
because  he  intends  to  do  something  little  [parvum).  Now 
according  to  the  Philosopher  [Prcedic.  Cap.  Ad  aliquid)  great 
and  little  are  relative  terms:  and  when  we  say  that  a  mean 
man  intends  to  do  something  little,  this  must  be  understood 
in  relation  to  the  kind  of  work  he  does.  This  may  be  little 
or  great  in  two  ways:  in  one  way  as  regards  the  work  itself 
to  be  done,  in  another  as  regards  the  expense.  Accordingly 
the  magnificent  man  intends  principally  the  greatness  of 
his  work,  and  secondarily  he  intends  the  greatness  of  the 
expense,  which  he  does  not  shirk,  so  that  he  may  produce 
a  great  work.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  iv.  4) 
that  the  magnificent  man  with  equal  expenditure  will  produce 
a  more  magnificent  result.  On  the  other  hand,  the  mean  man 
intends  principally  to  spend  little,  wherefore  the  Philosopher 
says  [Ethic,  iv.  2)  that  he  seeks  how  he  may  spend  least.  As 
a  result  of  this  he  intends  to  produce  a  little  work,  that  is, 
he  does  not  shrink  from  producing  a  little  work,  so  long  as 
he  spends  little.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  that  the 
mean  man  after  going  to  great  expense  forfeits  the  good  of  the 
magnificent  work,  for  the  trifle  that  he  is  unwilling  to  spend. 
Therefore  it  is  evident  that  the  mean  man  fails  to  observe 
the  proportion  that  reason  demands  betv/een  expenditure 
and  work.  Now  the  essence  of  vice  is  that  it  consists  in 
failing  to  do  what  is  in  accordance  with  reason.  Hence  it 
is  manifest  that  meanness  is  a  vice. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Virtue  moderates  little  things,  according 
to  the  rule  of  reason :  from  which  rule  the  mean  man  declines, 
as  stated  in  the  Article.  For  he  is  called  mean,  not  for 
moderating  little  things,  but  for  declining  from  the  rule  of 
reason  in  moderating  great  or  little  things :  hence  meanness 
is  a  vice. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  the  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.  5),  fear 
makes  us  take  counsel:  wherefore  a  mean  man  is  careful  in 
his  reckonings,  because  he  has  an  inordinate  fear  of  spending 
his  goods,  even  in  things  of  the  least  account.     Hence  this 


Q.  135.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  304 

is  not  praiseworthy,  but  sinful  and  reprehensible,  because 
then  a  man  does  not  regulate  his  affections  according  to 
reason,  but,  on  the  contrary,  makes  use  of  his  reason  in 
pursuance  of  his  inordinate  affections. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Just  as  the  magnificent  man  has  this  in 
common  with  the  liberal  man,  that  he  spends  his  money 
readily  and  with  pleasure,  so  too  the  mean  man  in  common 
with  the  illiberal  or  covetous  man  is  loth  and  slow  to  spend. 
Yet  they  differ  in  this,  that  illiberality  regards  ordinary 
expenditure,  while  meanness  regards  great  expenditure, 
which  is  a  more  difficult  accomplishment:  wherefore  mean- 
ness is  less  sinful  than  illiberality.  Hence  the  Philosopher 
says  {Ethic,  iv.  2)  that  although  meanness  and  its  contrary 
vice  are  sinful,  they  do  not  bring  shame  on  a  man,  since  neither 
do  they  harm  one's  neighbour,  nor  are  they  very  disgraceful. 

Second  Article, 
whether  there  is  a  vice  opposed  to  meanness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  there  is  no  vice  opposed  to 
meanness.  For  great  is  opposed  to  little.  Now,  magni- 
ficence is  not  a  vice,  but  a  virtue.  Therefore  no  vice  is 
opposed  to  meanness. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Since  meanness  is  a  vice  by  deficiency, 
as  stated  above  (A.  1),  it  seems  that  if  any  vice  is  opposed 
to  meanness,  it  would  merely  consist  in  excessive  spending. 
But  those  who  spend  much,  where  they  ought  to  spend 
little,  spend  little  where  they  ought  to  spend  much,  according 
to  Ethic,  iv.  2,  and  thus  they  have  something  of  meanness. 
Therefore  there  is  not  a  vice  opposed  to  meanness. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Moral  acts  take  their  species  from  their 
end,  as  stated  above  (A.  1).  Now  those  who  spend  exces- 
sively, do  so  in  order  to  make  a  show  of  their  wealth,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  iv.,  loc.  cit.  But  this  belongs  to  vainglory, 
which  is  opposed  to  magnanimity,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXXXI.,  A.  2).  Therefore  no  vice  is  opposed  to  mean- 
ness. 


305  MEANNESS  Q.  135.  Art.  2 

On  the  contrary  stands  the  authority  of  the  Philosopher 
who  (Ethic,  ii.  8;  iv.  2)  places  magnificence  as  a  mean  be- 
tween two  opposite  vices. 

/  answer  that,  Great  is  opposed  to  little.  Also  little  and 
great  are  relative  terms,  as  stated  above  (A.  1).  Now  just 
as  expenditure  may  be  little  in  comparison  with  the  work, 
so  may  it  be  great  in  comparison  with  the  work  in  that  it 
exceeds  the  proportion  which  reason  requires  to  exist  be- 
tween expenditure  and  work.  Hence  it  is  manifest  that 
the  vice  of  meanness,  whereby  a  man  intends  to  spend  less 
than  his  work  is  worth,  and  thus  fails  to  observe  due  pro- 
portion between  his  expenditure  and  his  work,  has  a  vice 
opposed  to  it,  whereby  a  man  exceeds  this  same  proportion, 
by  spending  more  than  is  proportionate  to  his  work.  This 
vice  is  called  in  Greek  fiavavala,  so  called  from  fiavvos, 
because,  like  the  fire  in  the  furnace,  it  consumes  everything. 
It  is  also  called  airvpoicaXia,  i.e.  lacking  good  fire,  since 
like  fire  it  consumes  all,  but  not  for  a  good  purpose.  Hence 
in  Latin  it  may  be  called  consumptio  (waste). 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Magnificence  is  so  called  from  the  great 
work  done,  but  not  from  the  expenditure  being  in  excess 
of  the  work:  for  this  belongs  to  the  vice  which  is  opposed 
to  meanness. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  To  the  one  same  vice  there  is  opposed  the 
virtue  which  observes  the  mean,  and  a  contrary  vice. 
Accordingly,  then,  the  vice  of  waste  is  opposed  to  mean- 
ness in  that  it  exceeds  in  expenditure  the  value  of  the  work, 
by  spending  much  where  it  behoved  to  spend  little.  But 
it  is  opposed  to  magnificence  on  the  part  of  the  great  work, 
which  the  magnificent  man  intends  principally,  in  so  far 
as  when  it  behoves  to  spend  much,  it  spends  little  or  nothing. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Wastefulness  is  opposed  to  meanness  by 
the  very  species  of  its  act,  since  it  exceeds  the  rule  of  reason, 
whereas  meanness  falls  short  of  it.  Yet  nothing  hinders 
this  from  being  directed  to  the  end  of  another  vice,  such  as 
vainglory  or  any  other. 


II.  H.  4  2Q 


QUESTION  CXXXVI. 

OF    PATIENCE. 

(In  Five  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  patience.  Under  this  head  there 
are  five  points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether  patience  is  a  virtue  ? 
(2)  Whether  it  is  the  greatest  of  the  virtues  ?  (3)  Whether 
it  can  be  had  without  grace  ?  (4)  Whether  it  is  a  part  of 
fortitude  ?     (5)  Whether  it  is  the  same  as  longanimity  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  patience  is  a  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  patience  is  not  a  virtue.  For 
the  virtues  are  most  perfect  in  heaven,  as  Augustine  says 
(De  Trin.  xiv.).  Yet  patience  is  not  there,  since  no  evils 
have  to  be  borne  there,  according  to  Isa.  xlix.  10  and 
Apoc.  vii.  16,  They  shall  not  hunger  nor  thirst,  neither  shall  the 
heat  nor  the  sun  strike  them.    Therefore  patience  is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  No  virtue  can  be  found  in  the  wicked, 
since  virtue  it  is  that  makes  its  subject  good.  Yet  patience 
is  sometimes  found  in  wicked  men;  for  instance,  in  the 
covetous,  who  bear  many  evils  patiently  that  they  may 
amass  money,  according  to  Eccles.  v.  16,  All  the  days  of  his 
life  he  eateth  in  darkness,  and  in  many  cares,  and  in  misery 
and  in  sorrow.     Therefore  patience  is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  fruits  differ  from  the  virtues,  as 
stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  LXX.,  A.  1,  ad  3).  But  patience 
is  reckoned  among  the  fruits  (Gal.  v.  22).  Therefore  patience 
is  not  a  virtue. 

306 


307  PATIENCE  Q.  136.  Art.  i 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Patientia  i.):  The 
virtue  of  the  soul  that  is  called  patience,  is  so  great  a  gift  of 
God,  that  we  even  preach  the  patience  of  Him  who  bestows  it 
upon  us. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  1),  the 
moral  virtues  are  directed  to  the  good,  inasmuch  as  they 
safeguard  the  good  of  reason  against  the  impulse  of  the 
passions.  Now  among  the  passions  sorrow  is  strong  to 
hinder  the  good  of  reason,  according  to  2  Cor.  vii.  10,  The 
sorrow  of  the  world  worketh  death,  and  Ecclus.  xxx.  25, 
Sadness  hath  killed  many,  and  there  is  no  profit  in  it.  Hence 
the  necessity  for  a  virtue  to  safeguard  the  good  of  reason 
against  sorrow,  lest  reason  give  way  to  sorrow:  and  this 
patience  does.  Wherefore  Augustine  says  {De  Patientia  ii.) : 
A  man's  patience  it  is  whereby  he  bears  evil  with  an  equal 
mind,  i.e.  without  being  disturbed  by  sorrow,  lest  he  abandon 
with  an  unequal  mind  the  goods  whereby  he  may  advance  to 
better  things.  It  is  therefore  evident  that  patience  is  a 
virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  moral  virtues  do  not  remain  in  heaven 
as  regards  the  same  act  that  they  have  on  the  way,  in  rela- 
tion, namely,  to  the  goods  of  the  present  life,  which  will  not 
remain  in  heaven:  but  they  will  remain  in  their  relation  to 
the  end,  which  will  be  in  heaven.  Thus  justice  will  not  be 
in  heaven  in  relation  to  buying  and  selling  and  other  matters 
pertaining  to  the  present  life,  but  it  will  remain  in  the  point 
of  being  subject  to  God.  In  like  manner  the  act  of  patience, 
in  heaven,  will  not  consist  in  bearing  things,  but  in  enjoying 
the  goods  to  which  we  had  aspired  by  suffering.  Hence 
Augustine  says  {De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  that  patience  itself  will 
not  be  in  heaven,  since  there  is  no  need  for  it  except  where  evils 
have  to  be  borne:  yet  that  which  we  shall  obtain  by  patience 
will  be  eternal. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  Augustine  says  {De  Patientia  ii:  v.) 
properly  speaking  those  are  patient  who  would  rather  bear 
evils  without  inflicting  them,  than  inflict  them  without  bearing 
them.  As  for  those  who  bear  evils  that  they  may  inflict  evil, 
their  patience  is  neither  marvellous  nor  praiseworthy,  for  it 


Q.  136.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  308 

is  no  patience  at  all :  we  may  marvel  at  their  hardness  of 
heart,  but  we  must  refuse  to  call  them  patient. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  XL,  A.  1),  the 
very  notion  of  fruit  denotes  pleasure.  And  works  of  virtue 
afford  pleasure  in  themselves,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  i.  8.  Now 
the  names  of  the  virtues  are  wont  to  be  applied  to  their  acts. 
Wherefore  patience  as  a  habit  is  a  virtue;  but  as  to  the 
pleasure  which  its  act  affords,  it  is  reckoned  a  fruit,  especially 
in  this,  that  patience  safeguards  the  mind  from  being 
overcome  by  sorrow. 

Second  Article, 
whether  patience  is  the  greatest  of  the  virtues  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  patience  is  the  greatest  of  the 
virtues.  For  in  every  genus  that  which  is  perfect  is  the 
greatest.  Now  patience  hath  a  perfect  work  (James  i.  4). 
Therefore  patience  is  the  greatest  of  the  virtues. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  All  the  virtues  are  directed  to  the  good 
of  the  soul.  Now  this  seems  to  belong  chiefly  to  patience ; 
for  it  is  written  (Luke  xxi.  19):  In  your  patience  you  shall 
possess  your  souls.  Therefore  patience  is  the  greatest  of 
the  virtues. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Seemingly  that  which  is  the  safeguard 
and  cause  of  other  things  is  greater  than  they  are.  But 
according  to  Gregory  (Horn.  xxxv.  in  Ev.)  patience  is  the 
root  and  safeguard  of  all  the  virtues.  Therefore  patience  is 
the  greatest  of  the  virtues. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  not  reckoned  among  the  four  virtues 
which  Gregory  [Moral,  xxii.)  and  Augustine  (De  Morib. 
Eccl.  xv.)  call  principal. 

/  answer  that,  Virtues  by  their  very  nature  are  directed 
to  good.  For  it  is  virtue  that  makes  its  subject  good,  and 
renders  the  latter  s  work  good  (Ethic,  ii.  6).  Hence  it  follows 
that  a  virtue's  superiority  and  preponderance  over  other 
virtues  is  the  greater  according  as  it  inclines  man  to  good 
more  effectively  and  directly.     Now  those  virtues  which 


309  PATIENCE  Q.  136.  Art.  2 

are  effective  of  good,  incline  man  more  directly  to  good  than 
those  which  are  a  check  on  the  things  which  lead  man  away 
from  good:  and  just  as  among  those  that  are  effective  of 
good,  the  greater  is  that  which  establishes  man  in  a  greater 
good  (thus  faith,  hope,  and  charity  are  greater  than  pru- 
dence and  justice);  so  too  among  those  that  are  a  check  on 
things  that  withdraw  man  from  good,  the  greater  virtue  is 
the  one  which  is  a  check  on  a  greater  obstacle  to  good. 
But  dangers  of  death,  about  which  is  fortitude,  and  pleasures 
of  touch,  with  which  temperance  is  concerned,  withdraw 
man  from  good  more  than  any  kind  of  hardship,  which  is 
the  object  of  patience.  Therefore  patience  is  not  the  greatest 
of  the  virtues,  but  falls  short,  not  only  of  the  theological 
virtues,  and  of  prudence  and  justice  which  directly  establish 
man  in  good,  but  .also  of  fortitude  and  temperance  which 
withdraw  him  from  greater  obstacles  to  good. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Patience  is  said  to  have  a  perfect  work  in 
bearing  hardships :  for  these  give  rise  first  to  sorrow,  which 
is  moderated  by  patience;  secondly,  to  anger,  which  is 
moderated  by  meekness ;  thirdly,  to  hatred,  which  charity 
removes;  fourthly,  to  unjust  injury,  which  justice  for- 
bids. Now  that  which  removes  the  principle  is  the  most 
perfect. 

Yet  it  does  not  follow,  if  patience  be  more  perfect  in  this 
respect,  that  it  is  more  perfect  simply. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Possession  denotes  undisturbed  ownership; 
wherefore  man  is  said  to  possess  his  soul  by  patience,  in  so 
far  as  it  removes  by  the  root  the  passions  that  are  evoked 
by  hardships  and  disturb  the  soul. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Patience  is  said  to  be  the  root  and  safe- 
guard of  all  the  virtues,  not  as  though  it  caused  and 
preserved  them  directly,  but  merely  because  it  removes  their 
obstacles. 


Q.  136.  Art.  3    THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  310 


Third  Article, 
whether  it  is  possible  to  have  patience  without 

GRACE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  it  is  possible  to  have  patience 
without  grace.  For  the  more  his  reason  inclines  to  a  thing, 
the  more  is  it  possible  for  the  rational  creature  to  accom- 
plish it.  Now  it  is  more  reasonable  to  suffer  evil  for  the  sake 
of  good  than  for  the  sake  of  evil.  Yet  some  suffer  evil  for 
evil's  sake,  by  their  own  virtue  and  without  the  help  of 
grace;  for  Augustine  says  (De  Patientia  iii.)  that  men  endure 
many  toils  and  sorrows  for  the  sake  of  the  things  they  love  sin- 
fully. Much  more,  therefore,  is  it  possible  for  man,  without 
the  help  of  grace,  to  bear  evil  for  the  sake  of  good,  and  this 
is  to  be  truly  patient. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Some  who  are  not  in  a  state  of  grace 
have  more  abhorrence  for  sinful  evils  than  for  bodily  evils: 
hence  some  heathens  are  related  to  have  endured  many 
hardships  rather  than  betray  their  country  or  commit  some 
other  misdeed.  Now  this  is  to  be  truly  patient.  Therefore 
it  seems  that  it  is  possible  to  have  patience  without  the  help 
of  grace. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  is  quite  evident  that  some  go  through 
much  trouble  and  pain  in  order  to  regain  health  of  the  body. 
Now  the  health  of  the  soul  is  not  less  desirable  than  bodily 
health.  Therefore  in  like  manner  one  may,  without  the 
help  of  grace,  endure  many  evils  for  the  health  of  the  soul, 
and  this  is  to  be  truly  patient . 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  lxi.  6):  From  Him,  i.e. 
from  God,  is  my  patience. 

I  answer  that,  As  Augustine  says  {De  Patientia  iv.),  the 
strength  of  desire  helps  a  man  to  bear  toil  and  pain:  and  no  one 
willingly  undertakes  to  bear  what  is  painful,  save  for  the  sake 
of  that  which  gives  pleasure.  The  reason  of  this  is  because 
sorrow  and  pain  are  of  themselves  displeasing  to  the  soul, 
wherefore  it  would  never  choose  to  suffer  them  for  their 


3H  PATIENCE  Q.  136.  Art.  3 

own  sake,  but  only  for  the  sake  of  an  end.  Hence  it  follows 
that  the  good  for  the  sake  of  which  one  is  willing  to  endure 
evils,  is  more  desired  and  loved  than  the  good  the  privation 
of  which  causes  the  sorrow  that  we  bear  patiently.  Now 
the  fact  that  a  man  prefers  the  good  of  grace  to  all  natural 
goods,  the  loss  of  which  may  cause  sorrow,  is  to  be  referred 
to  charity,  which  loves  God  above  all  things.  Hence  it  is 
evident  that  patience,  as  a  virtue,  is  caused  by  charity, 
according  to  1  Cor.  xiii.  4,  Charity  is  patient. 

But  it  is  manifest  that  it  is  impossible  to  have  charity 
save  through  grace,  according  to  Rom.  v.  5,  The  charity  of 
God  is  poured  forth  in  our  hearts  by  the  Holy  Ghost  Who  is 
given  to  us.  Therefore  it  is  clearly  impossible  to  have 
patience  without  the  help  of  grace. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  inclination  of  reason  would  prevail  in 
human  nature  in  the  state  of  integrity.  But  in  corrupt 
nature  the  inclination  of  concupiscence  prevails,  because  it 
is  dominant  in  man.  Hence  man  is  more  prone  to  bear  evils 
for  the  sake  of  goods  in  which  the  concupiscence  delights 
here  and  now,  than  to  endure  evils  for  the  sake  of  goods  to 
come,  which  are  desired  in  accordance  with  reason:  and 
yet  it  is  this  that  pertains  to  true  patience. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  good  of  a  social  virtue*  is  commensurate 
with  human  nature;  and  consequently  the  human  will  can 
tend  thereto  without  the  help  of  sanctifying  grace,  yet  not 
without  the  help  of  God's  grace,  f  On  the  other  hand,  the 
good  of  grace  is  supernatural,  wherefore  man  cannot  tend 
thereto  by  a  natural  virtue.     Hence  the  comparison  fails. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Even  the  endurance  of  those  evils  which  a 
man  bears  for  the  sake  of  his  body's  health,  proceeds  from 
the  love  a  man  naturally  has  for  his  own  flesh.  Hence 
there  is  no  comparison  between  this  endurance  and  patience 
which  proceeds  from  a  supernatural  love. 

*  Cf.  I.-IL,  Q.  LXI.,  A.  5.  f  Cf.  I.-IL,  Q.  CIX.,  A.  2. 


Q.  136.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  312 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  patience  is  a  part  of  fortitude  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  patience  is  not  a  part  of  forti- 
tude. For  a  thing  is  not  part  of  itself.  Now  patience  is 
apparently  the  same  as  fortitude:  because,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  6),  the  proper  act  of  fortitude  is  to  endure; 
and  this  belongs  also  to  patience.  For  it  is  stated  in  the 
Liber  Sententiarum  Prosperi*  that  patience  consists  in  en- 
during evils  inflicted  by  others.  Therefore  patience  is  not  a 
part  of  fortitude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Fortitude  is  about  fear  and  daring,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  3),  and  thus  it  is  in  the  iras- 
cible. But  patience  seems  to  be  about  sorrow,  and  conse- 
quently would  seem  to  be  in  the  concupiscible.  Therefore 
patience  is  not  a  part  of  fortitude  but  of  temperance. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  whole  cannot  be  without  its  part. 
Therefore  if  patience  is  a  part  of  fortitude,  there  can  be  no 
fortitude  without  patience.  Yet  sometimes  a  brave  man 
does  not  endure  evils  patiently,  but  even  attacks  the  person 
who  inflicts  the  evil.  Therefore  patience  is  not  a  part  of 
fortitude. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  reckons  it  a  part 
of  fortitude. 

/  answer  that,  Patience  is  a  quasi-potential  part  of  forti- 
tude, because  it  is  annexed  thereto  as  secondary  to  principal 
virtue.  For  it  belongs  to  patience  to  suffer  with  an  equal 
mind  the  evils  inflicted  by  others,  as  Gregory  says  in  a  homily 
(xxxv.  in  Ev.).  Now  of  those  evils  that  are  inflicted  by 
others,  foremost  and  most  difficult  to  endure  are  those  that 
are  connected  with  the  danger  of  death,  and  about  these 
evils  fortitude  is  concerned.  Hence  it  is  clear  that  in  this 
matter  fortitude  has  the  principal  place,  and  that  it  lays 
claim  to  that  which  is  principal  in  this  matter.  Wherefore 
patience  is  annexed  to  fortitude  as  secondary  to  principal 

*  The  quotation  is  from  S.  Gregory  (Horn.  xxxv.  in  Ev.). 


313  PATIENCE  Q.  136.  Art.  4 

virtue,    for    which    reason    Prosper    calls    patience    brave 
(Sent.  811). 

Reply  Obj.  1.  It  belongs  to  fortitude  to  endure,  not  any- 
thing indeed,  but  that  which  is  most  difficult  to  endure, 
namely  dangers  of  death :  whereas  it  may  pertain  to  patience 
to  endure  any  kind  of  evil. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  act  of  fortitude  consists  not  only  in 
holding  fast  to  good  against  the  fear  of  future  dangers,  but 
also  in  not  failing  through  sorrow  or  pain  occasioned  by 
things  present;  and  it  is  in  the  latter  respect  that  patience 
is  akin  to  fortitude.  Yet  fortitude  is  chiefly  about  fear, 
which  of  itself  evokes  flight  which  fortitude  avoids;  while 
patience  is  chiefly  about  sorrow,  for  a  man  is  said  to  be 
patient,  not  because  he  does  not  fly,  but  because  he  behaves 
in  a  praiseworthy  manner  by  suffering  (patiendo)  things 
which  hurt  him  here  and  now,  in  such  a  way  as  not  to  be 
inordinately  saddened  by  them.  Hence  fortitude  is  properly 
in  the  irascible,  while  patience  is  in  the  concupiscible 
faculty. 

Nor  does  this  hinder  patience  from  being  a  part  of  forti- 
tude, because  the  annexing  of  virtue  to  virtue  does  not 
regard  the  subject,  but  the  matter  or  the  form.  Neverthe- 
less patience  is  not  to  be  reckoned  a  part  of  temperance, 
although  both  are  in  the  concupiscible,  because  temperance 
is  only  about  those  sorrows  that  are  opposed  to  pleasures 
of  touch,  such  as  arise  through  abstinence  from  pleasures 
of  food  and  sex:  whereas  patience  is  chiefly  about  sorrows 
inflicted  by  other  persons.  Moreover  it  belongs  to  tem- 
perance to  control  these  sorrows  besides  their  contrary 
pleasures :  whereas  it  belongs  to  patience  that  a  man  forsake 
not  the  good  of  virtue  on  account  of  suchlike  sorrows, 
however  great  they  be. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  It  may  be  granted  that  patience  in  a  certain 
respect  is  an  integral  part  of  justice,  if  we  consider  the  fact 
that  a  man  may  patiently  endure  evils  pertaining  to  dangers 
of  death;  and  it  is  from  this  point  of  view  that  the  objection 
argues.  Nor  is  it  inconsistent  with  patience  that  a  man 
should,  when  necessary,  rise  up  against  the  man  who  inflicts 


Q.  136.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  314 

evils  on  him;  for  Chrysostom*  says  on  Matth.  iv.  10,  Begone 
Satan,  that  it  is  praiseworthy  to  be  patient  under  our  own 
wrongs,  but  to  endure  God's  wrongs  patiently  is  most  wicked : 
and  Augustine  says  in  a  letter  to  Marcellinus  (Ep.  cxxxviii.) 
that  the  precepts  of  pacience  are  not  opposed  to  the  good  of  the 
commonwealth,  since  in  order  to  ensure  that  good  we  fight 
against  our  enemies.  But  in  so  far  as  patience  regards  all 
kinds  of  evils,  it  is  annexed  to  fortitude  as  secondary  to 
principal  virtue. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  patience  is  the  same  as  longanimity  ?t 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  patience  is  the  same  as  longa- 
nimity. For  Augustine  says  (De  Patientia  i.)  that  we  speak 
of  patience  in  God,  not  as  though  any  evil  made  Him  suffer, 
but  because  He  awaits  the  wicked,  that  they  may  be  converted. 
Wherefore  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  v.  4) :  The  Most  High  is  a 
patient  rewarder.  Therefore  it  seems  that  patience  is  the 
same  as  longanimity. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  same  thing  is  not  contrary  to  two 
things.  But  impatience  is  contrary  to  longanimity,  whereby 
one  awaits  a  delay :  for  one  is  said  to  be  impatient  of  delay, 
as  of  other  evils.  Therefore  it  seems  that  patience  is  the 
same  as  longanimity. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Just  as  time  is  a  circumstance  of  wrongs 
endured,  so  is  place.  But  no  virtue  is  distinct  from  patience 
on  the  score  of  place.  Therefore  in  like  manner  longanimity 
which  takes  count  of  time,  in  so  far  as  a  person  waits  for  a 
long  time,  is  not  distinct  from  patience. 

Obj.  4.  On  the  contrary,  a  glossj  on  Rom.  ii.  4,  Or  despisest 
thou  the  riches  of  His  goodness,  and  patience,  and  longsuffer- 
ing?  says:   It  seems  that  longanimity  differs  from  patience, 

*  Homily  v.  in  the  Opus  Imperfectum,  falsely  ascribed  to  S.  John 
Chrysostom. 

f  Longsuffering.  It  is  necessary  to  preserve  the  Latin  word,  on 
account  of  the  comparison  with  magnanimity. 

I  Origen,  Comment  in  Ep.  ad  Rom.  ii. 


315  PATIENCE  Q.  136.  Art.  5 

because  those  who  offend  from  weakness  rather  than  of  set  purpose 
are  said  to  be  borne  with  longanimity:  while  those  who  take  a 
deliberate  delight  in  their  crimes  are  said  to  be  borne  patiently. 

I  answer  that,  Just  as  by  magnanimity  a  man  has  a  mind 
to  tend  to  great  things,  so  by  longanimity  a  man  has  a  mind 
to  tend  to  something  a  long  way  off.  Wherefore  as  magna- 
nimity regards  hope,  which  tends  to  good,  rather  than  daring, 
fear,  or  sorrow,  which  have  evil  as  their  object,  so  also  does 
longanimity.  Hence  longanimity  has  more  in  common 
with  magnanimity  than  with  patience. 

Nevertheless  it  may  have  something  in  common  with 
patience,  for  two  reasons.  First,  because  patience,  like 
fortitude,  endures  certain  evils  for  the  sake  of  good,  and  if 
this  good  is  awaited  shortly,  endurance  is  easier:  whereas 
if  it  be  delayed  a  long  time,  it  is  more  difficult.  Secondly, 
because  the  very  delay  of  the  good  we  hope  for,  is  of  a  nature 
to  cause  sorrow,  according  to  Prov.  xiii.  12,  Hope  that  is 
deferred  afflicteth  the  soul.  Hence  there  may  be  patience 
in  bearing  this  trial,  as  in  enduring  any  other  sorrows. 
Accordingly  longanimity  and  constancy  are  both  comprised 
under  patience,  in  so  far  as  both  the  delay  of  the  hoped  for 
good  (which  regards  longanimity)  and  the  toil  which  man 
endures  in  persistently  accomplishing  a  good  work  (which 
regards  constancy)  may  be  considered  under  the  one  aspect 
of  grievous  evil. 

For  this  reason  Tully  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  in  defining  patience, 
says  that  patience  is  the  voluntary  and  prolonged  endurance 
of  arduous  and  difficult  things  for  the  sake  of  virtue  or  profit. 
By  saying  arduous  he  refers  to  constancy  in  good;  when  he 
says  difficult  he  refers  to  the  grievousness  of  evil,  which  is 
the  proper  object  of  patience;  and  by  adding  continued  or 
long  lasting,  he  refers  to  longanimity,  in  so  far  as  it  has 
something  in  common  with  patience. 

This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  First  and  Second  Objec- 
tions. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  That  which  is  a  long  way  off  as  to  place, 
though  distant  from  us,  is  not  simply  distant  from  things 
in  nature,  as  that  which  is  a  long  way  off  in  point  of  time : 


Q.  136.  Art.  5     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  316 

hence  the  comparison  fails.  Moreover,  what  is  remote  as 
to  place  offers  no  difficulty  save  in  the  point  of  time,  since 
what  is  placed  a  long  way  from  us  is  a  long  time  coming  to  us. 
We  grant  the  fourth  argument.  We  must  observe, 
however,  that  the  reason  for  the  difference  assigned  by  this 
gloss  is  that  it  is  hard  to  bear  with  those  who  sin  through 
weakness,  merely  because  they  persist  a  long  time  in 
evil,  wherefore  it  is  said  that  they  are  borne  with  longa- 
nimity :  whereas  the  very  fact  of  sinning  through  pride  seems 
to  be  unendurable;  for  which  reason  those  who  sin  through 
pride  are  stated  to  be  borne  with  patience. 


QUESTION  CXXXVII. 

OF  PERSEVERANCE. 

(In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  perseverance  and  the  vices  opposed 
to  it.  Under  the  head  of  perseverance  there  are  four 
points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether  perseverance  is  a  virtue  ? 
(2)  Whether  it  is  a  part  of  fortitude  ?  (3)  Of  its  relation  to 
con  -tancy :   (4)  Whether  it  needs  the  help  of  grace  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  perseverance  is  a  virtue  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  perseverance  is  not  a  virtue. 
For,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  vii.  7),  continency 
is  greater  than  perseverance.  But  continency  is  not  a 
virtue,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iv.  9.  Therefore  perseverance  is 
not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  By  virtue  man  lives  aright,  according  to 
Augustine  (De  Lib.  Arb.  ii.  19).  Now  according  to  the  same 
authority  (De  Per  sever,  i.),  no  one  can  be  said  to  have  per- 
severance while  living,  unless  he  persevere  until  death.  There- 
fore perseverance  is  not  a  virtue. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  It  is  requisite  of  every  virtue  that  one 
should  persist  unchangeably  in  the  work  of  that  virtue,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  ii.  4.  But  this  is  what  we  understand  by 
perseverance:  for  Tully  says  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  perse- 
verance is  the  fixed  and  continued  persistence  in  a  well-con- 
sidered purpose.  Therefore  perseverance  is  not  a  special 
virtue,  but  a  condition  of  every  virtue. 

317 


Q.  i37-  Art.  i     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  318 

On  the  contrary,  Andronicus*  says  that  perseverance  is  a 
habit  regarding  things  to  which  we  ought  to  stand,  and  those 
to  which  we  ought  not  to  stand,  as  well  as  those  that  are  in- 
different. Now  a  habit  that  directs  us  to  do  something 
well,  or  to  omit  something,  is  a  virtue.  Therefore  perse- 
verance is  a  virtue. 

I  answer  that,  According  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  ii.  3), 
virtue  is  about  the  difficult  and  the  good;  and  so  where  there  is 
a  special  kind  of  difficulty  or  goodness,  there  is  a  special 
virtue.  Now  a  virtuous  deed  may  involve  goodness  or 
difficulty  on  two  counts.  First,  from  the  act's  very  species, 
which  is  considered  in  respect  of  the  proper  object  of  that 
act :  secondly,  from  the  length  of  time,  since  to  persist  long 
in  something  difficult  involves  a  special  difficulty.  Hence 
to  persist  long  in  something  good  until  it  is  accomplished 
belongs  to  a  special  virtue. 

Accordingly  just  as  temperance  and  fortitude  are  special 
virtues,  for  the  reason  that  the  one  moderates  pleasures  of 
touch  (which  is  of  itself  a  difficult  thing),  while  the  other 
moderates  fear  and  daring  in  connexion  with  dangers  of 
death  (which  also  is  something  difficult  in  itself),  so  persever- 
ance is  a  special  virtue,  since  it  consists  in  enduring  delays  in 
the  above  or  other  virtuous  deeds,  so  far  as  necessity  requires. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  Philosopher  is  taking  perseverance 
there,  as  it  is  found  in  one  who  bears  those  things  which  are 
most  difficult  to  endure  long.  Now  it  is  difficult  to  endure, 
not  good,  but  evil.  And  evils  that  involve  danger  of  death, 
for  the  most  part  are  not  endured  for  a  long  time,  because 
often  they  soon  pass  away :  wherefore  it  is  not  on  this  account 
that  perseverance  has  its  chief  title  to  praise.  Among 
other  evils  foremost  are  those  which  are  opposed  to  pleasures 
of  touch,  because  evils  of  this  kind  affect  the  necessaries  of 
life :  such  are  the  lack  of  food  and  the  like,  which  at  times 
call  for  long  endurance.  Now  it  is  not  difficult  to  endure 
these  things  for  a  long  time  for  one  who  grieves  not  much 
at  them,  nor  delights  much  in  the  contrary  goods ;  as  in  the 
case  of  the  temperate  man,  in  whom  these  passions  are  not 
violent.     But  they  are  most  difficult  to  bear  for  one  who  is 

*  Chrysippus :  in  De  Affect. 


319  PERSEVERANCE  Q.  137.  Art.  i 

strongly  affected  by  such  things,  through  lacking  the  perfect 
virtue  that  moderates  these  passions.  Wherefore  if  perse- 
verance be  taken  in  this  sense  it  is  not  a  perfect  virtue,  but 
something  imperfect  in  the  genus  of  virtue.  On  the  other 
hand,  if  we  take  perseverance  as  denoting  long  persistence 
in  any  kind  of  difficult  good,  it  is  consistent  in  one  who  has 
even  perfect  virtue :  for  even  if  it  is  less  difficult  for  him  to 
persist,  yet  he  persists  in  the  more  perfect  good.  Where- 
fore suchlike  perseverance  may  be  a  virtue,  because  virtue 
derives  perfection  from  the  aspect  of  good  rather  than  from 
the  aspect  of  difficulty. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Sometimes  a  virtue  and  its  act  go  by  the 
same  name:  thus  Augustine  says  {Tract,  in  Joan,  lxxix.): 
Faith  is  to  believe  without  seeing.  Yet  it  is  possible  to  have 
a  habit  of  virtue  without  performing  the  act:  thus  a  poor 
man  has  the  habit  of  magnificence  without  exercising  the 
act.  Sometimes,  however,  a  person  who  has  the  habit, 
begins  to  perform  the  act,  yet  does  not  accomplish  it,  for 
instance  a  builder  begins  to  build  a  house,  but  does  not 
complete  it.  Accordingly  we  must  reply  that  the  term 
perseverance  is  sometimes  used  to  denote  the  habit  whereby 
one  chooses  to  persevere,  sometimes  for  the  act  of  perse- 
vering: and  sometimes  one  who  has  the  habit  of  perseverance 
chooses  to  persevere  and  begins  to  carry  out  his  choice  by 
persisting  for  a  time,  yet  completes  not  the  act,  through  not 
persisting  to  the  end.  Now  the  end  is  twofold :  one  is  the 
end  of  the  work,  the  other  is  the  end  of  human  life.  Properly 
speaking  it  belongs  to  perseverance  to  persevere  to  the  end 
of  the  virtuous  work,  for  instance  that  a  soldier  persevere 
to  the  end  of  the  fight,  and  the  magnificent  man  until  his 
work  be  accomplished.  There  are,  however,  some  virtues 
whose  acts  must  endure  throughout  the  whole  of  life,  such 
as  faith,  hope,  and  charity,  since  they  regard  the  last  end 
of  the  entire  life  of  man.  Wherefore  as  regards  these  which 
are  the  principal  virtues,  the  act  of  perseverance  is  not 
accomplished  until  the  end  of  life.  It  is  in  this  sense  that 
Augustine  speaks  of  perseverance  as  denoting  the  consum- 
mate act  of  perseverance. 


Q.  137.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  320 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Unchangeable  persistence  may  belong  to 
a  virtue  in  two  ways.  First,  on  account  of  the  intended  end 
that  is  proper  to  that  virtue ;  and  thus  to  persist  in  good  for 
a  long  time  until  the  end,  belongs  to  a  special  virtue  called 
perseverance,  which  intends  this  as  its  special  end.  Secondly, 
by  reason  of  the  relation  of  the  habit  to  its  subject :  and  thus 
unchangeable  persistence  is  consequent  upon  every  virtue, 
inasmuch  as  virtue  is  a  quality  difficult  to  change. 

Second  Article, 
whether  perseverance  is  a  part  of  fortitude  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  perseverance  is  not  a  part  of 
fortitude.  For,  according  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  viii.  7), 
perseverance  is  about  pains  of  touch.  But  these  belong  to 
temperance.  Therefore  perseverance  is  a  part  of  temper- 
ance rather  than  of  fortitude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Every  part  of  a  moral  virtue  is  about 
certain  passions  which  that  virtue  moderates.  Now  perse- 
verance does  not  imply  moderation  of  the  passions:  since 
the  more  violent  the  passions,  the  more  praiseworthy  is  it 
to  persevere  in  accordance  with  reason.  Therefore  it  seems 
that  perseverance  is  a  part  not  of  a  moral  virtue,  but  rather 
of  prudence  which  perfects  the  reason. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  (De  Persev.  i.)  that  no 
one  can  lose  perseverance;  whereas  one  can  lose  the  other 
virtues.  Therefore  perseverance  is  greater  than  all  the 
other  virtues.  Now  a  principal  virtue  is  greater  than  its 
part.  Therefore  perseverance  is  not  a  part  of  a  virtue, 
but  is  itself  a  principal  virtue. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  reckons  perse- 
verance as  a  part  of  fortitude. 

J  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  2:  I.  II., 
Q.  LXL,  AA.  3,  4),  a  principal  virtue  is  one  to  which  is 
principally  ascribed  something  that  lays  claim  to  the  praise 
of  virtue,  inasmuch  as  it  practises  it  in  connexion  with  its 
own  matter,  wherein  it  is  most  difficult  of  accomplishment. 


321  PERSEVERANCE  Q.  137-  Art.  2 

In  accordance  with  this  it  has  been  stated  (0.  CXXIII.,  A.  2) 
that  fortitude  is  a  principal  virtue,  because  it  observes 
firmness  in  matters  wherein  it  is  most  difficult  to  stand  firm, 
namely  in  dangers  of  death.  Wherefore  it  follows  of  neces- 
sity that  every  virtue  which  has  a  title  to  praise  for  the  firm 
endurance  of  something  difficult  must  be  annexed  to  forti- 
tude as  secondary  to  principal  virtue.  Now  the  endurance 
of  difficulty  arising  from  delay  in  accomplishing  a  good 
work  gives  perseverance  its  claim  to  praise:  nor  is  this  so 
difficult  as  to  endure  dangers  of  death.  Therefore  perse- 
verance is  annexed  to  fortitude,  as  secondary  to  principal 
virtue. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  annexing  of  secondary  to  principal 
virtues  depends  not  only  on  the  matter,*  but  also  on  the 
mode,  because  in  everything  form  is  of  more  account  than 
matter.  Wherefore  although,  as  to  matter,  perseverance 
seems  to  have  more  in  common  with  temperance  than 
with  fortitude,  yet,  in  mode,  it  has  more  in  common  with 
fortitude,  in  the  point  of  standing  firm  against  the  difficulty 
arising  from  length  of  time. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  perseverance  of  which  the  Philosopher 
speaks  (Ethic,  vii.  4,  7)  does  not  moderate  any  passions,  but 
consists  merely  in  a  certain  firmness  of  reason  and  will. 
But  perseverance,  considered  as  a  virtue,  moderates  certain 
passions,  namely  fear  of  weariness  or  failure  on  account  of 
the  delay.  Hence  this  virtue,  like  fortitude,  is  in  the 
irascible. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Augustine  speaks  there  of  perseverance,  as 
denoting,  not  a  virtuous  habit,  but  a  virtuous  act  sustained 
to  the  end,  according  to  Matth.  xxiv.  13,  He  that  shall  perse- 
vere to  the  end,  he  shall  he  saved.  Hence  it  is  incompatible 
with  suchlike  perseverance  for  it  to  be  lost,  since  it  would  no 
longer  endure  to  the  end. 

*  Cf.  Q.  CXXXVI.,  A.  4  ad  2. 


11.  ii.  4  21 


Q.  137.  Art.  3     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  322 


Third  Article, 
whether  constancy  pertains  to  perseverance  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  constancy  does  not  pertain  to 
perseverance.  For  constancy  pertains  to  patience,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  CXXXVIL,  A.  5):  and  patience  differs 
from  perseverance.  Therefore  constancy  does  not  pertain 
to  perseverance. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Virtue  is  about  the  difficult  and  the  good. 
Now  it  does  not  seem  difficult  to  be  constant  in  little  works, 
but  only  in  great  deeds,  which  pertain  to  magnificence. 
Therefore  constancy  pertains  to  magnificence  rather  than 
to  perseverance. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  If  constancy  pertained  to  perseverance, 
it  would  seem  nowise  to  differ  from  it,  since  both  denote 
a  kind  of  unchangeableness.  Yet  they  differ:  for  Macro- 
bius  (De  Somn.  Scip.  i.)  condivides  constancy  with  firm- 
ness by  which  he  indicates  perseverance,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXXVIIL,  A.  6).  Therefore  constancy  does  not  pertain 
to  perseverance. 

On  the  contrary,  One  is  said  to  be  constant  because  one 
stands  to  a  thing.  Now  it  belongs  to  perseverance  to  stand 
to  certain  things,  as  appears  from  the  definition  given  by 
Andronicus.     Therefore  constancy  belongs  to  perseverance. 

I  answer  that,  Perseverance  and  constancy  agree  as  to 
end,  since  it  belongs  to  both  to  persist  firmly  in  some  good: 
but  they  differ  as  to  those  things  which  make  it  difficult  to 
persist  in  good.  Because  the  virtue  of  perseverance  properly 
makes  man  persist  firmly  in  good,  against  the  difficulty  that 
arises  from  the  very  continuance  of  the  act:  whereas  con- 
stancy makes  him  persist  firmly  in  good  against  difficulties 
arising  from  any  other  external  hindrances.  Hence  perse- 
verance takes  precedence  of  constancy  as  a  part  of  fortitude, 
because  the  difficulty  arising  from  continuance  of  action 
is  more  intrinsic  to  the  act  of  virtue  than  that  which  arises 
from  external  obstacles. 


323  PERSEVERANCE  Q.  137-  Art.  4 

Reply  Obj.  1.  External  obstacles  to  persistence  in  good 
are  especially  those  which  cause  sorrow.  Now  patience  is 
about  sorrow,  as  stated  above  (Q.  CXXXVL,  A.  1).  Hence 
constancy  agrees  with  perseverance  as  to  end :  while  it  agrees 
with  patience  as  to  those  things  which  occasion  difficulty. 
Now  the  end  is  of  most  account :  wherefore  constancy  per- 
tains to  perseverance  rather  than  to  patience. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  is  more  difficult  to  persist  in  great  deeds: 
yet  in  little  or  ordinary  deeds,  it  is  difficult  to  persist  for  any 
length  of  time,  if  not  on  account  of  the  greatness  of  the  deed 
which  magnificence  considers,  yet  from  its  very  continuance 
which  perseverance  regards.  Hence  constancy  may  pertain 
to  both. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Constancy  pertains  to  perseverance  in  so 
far  as  it  has  something  in  common  with  it :  but  it  is  not  the 
same  thing  in  the  point  of  their  difference,  as  stated  in  the 
Article. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  perseverance  needs  the  help  of  grace  ?* 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  perseverance  does  not  need  the 
help  of  grace.  For  perseverance  is  a  virtue,  as  stated  above 
(A.  1).  Now  according  to  Tully  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  virtue 
acts  after  the  manner  of  nature.  Therefore  the  sole  inclina- 
tion of  virtue  suffices  for  perseverance.  Therefore  this  does 
not  need  the  help  of  grace. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  gift  of  Christ's  grace  is  greater  than 
the  harm  brought  upon  us  by  Adam,  as  appears  from 
Rom.  v.  15  seq.  Now  before  sin  man  was  so  framed  that 
he  could  persevere  by  means  of  what  he  had  received,  as  Augus- 
tine says  {De  Correp.  et  Grat.  xi.).  Much  more  therefore 
can  man,  after  being  repaired  by  the  grace  of  Christ,  perse- 
vere without  the  help  of  a  further  grace. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Sinful  deeds  are  sometimes  more  difficult 
than  deeds  of  virtue:  hence  it  is  said  in  the  person  of  the 
wicked  (Wis.  v.  7) :  We  .  .  .  have  walked  through  hard  ways. 

*  Cf.  I.-IL,  Q.  CIX.,  A.  10. 


Q.  137.  Art.  4     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  324 

Now  some  persevere  in  sinful  deeds  without  the  help  of 
another.  Therefore  man  can  also  persevere  in  deeds  of 
virtue  without  the  help  of  grace. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Persev.  i.):  We  hold 
that  perseverance  is  a  gift  of  God,  whereby  we  persevere  unto 
the  end,  in  Christ. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  1,  ad  2:  A.  2,  ad  3), 
perseverance  has  a  twofold  signification.  First,  it  denotes 
the  habit  of  perseverance,  considered  as  a  virtue.  In  this 
way  it  needs  the  gift  of  habitual  grace,  even  as  the  other 
infused  virtues.  Secondly,  it  may  be  taken  to  denote  the 
act  of  perseverance  enduring  until  death:  and  in  this  sense 
it  needs  not  only  habitual  grace,  but  also  the  gratuitous 
help  of  God  sustaining  man  in  good  until  the  end  of  life,  as 
stated  above  (I. -II.,  Q.  CIX.,  A.  10),  when  we  were  treating 
of  grace.  Because,  since  the  free-will  is  changeable  by  its 
very  nature,  which  changeableness  is  not  taken  away  from 
it  by  the  habitual  grace  bestowed  in  the  present  life,  it  is 
not  in  the  power  of  the  free-will,  albeit  repaired  by  grace, 
to  abide  unchangeably  in  good,  though  it  is  in  its  power  to 
choose  this:  for  it  is  often  in  our  power  to  choose  yet  not  to 
accomplish. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  virtue  of  perseverance,  so  far  as  it  is 
concerned,  inclines  one  to  persevere:  yet  since  it  is  a  habit, 
and  a  habit  is  a  thing  one  uses  at  will,  it  does  not  follow 
that  a  person  who  has  the  habit  of  virtue  uses  it  unchange- 
ably until  death. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  Augustine  says  (De  Correp.  et  Grat.  xi.), 
it  was  given  to  the  first  man,  not  to  persevere,  but  to  be  able  to 
persevere  of  his  free-will:  because  then  no  corruption  was  in 
human  nature  to  make  perseverance  difficult.  Now,  however, 
by  the  grace  of  Christ,  the  predestined  receive  not  only  the 
possibility  of  persevering,  but  perseverance  itself.  Wherefore 
the  first  man  whom  no  man  threatened,  of  his  own  free-will 
rebelling  against  a  threatening  God,  forfeited  so  great  a  hap- 
piness and  so  great  a  facility  of  avoiding  sin:  whereas  these, 
although  the  world  rage  against  their  constancy,  have  persevered 
in  faith. 


325  PERSEVERANCE  Q.  137-  Art.  4 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Man  is  able  by  himself  to  fall  into  sin,  but 
he  cannot  by  himself  arise  from  sin  without  the  help  of 
grace.  Hence  by  falling  into  sin,  so  far  as  he  is  concerned 
man  makes  himself  to  be  persevering  in  sin,  unless  he  be 
delivered  by  God's  grace.  On  the  other  hand,  by  doing 
good  he  does  not  make  himself  to  be  persevering  in  good, 
because  he  is  able,  by  himself,  to  sin:  wherefore  he  needs 
the  help  of  grace  for  that  end. 


QUESTION  CXXXVIIL 

OF  THE  VICES  OPPOSED  TO  PERSEVERANCE. 

(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  vices  opposed  to  perseverance; 
under  which  head  there  are  two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Of 
effeminacy;  (2)  Of  pertinacity. 

First  Article, 
whether  effeminacy*  is  opposed  to  perseverance  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  effeminacy  is  not  opposed  to 
perseverance.  For  a  gloss  on  1  Cor.  vi.  9,  10,  Nor  adulterers, 
nor  the  effeminate,  nor  Hers  with  mankind,  expounds  the  text 
thus:  Effeminate — i.e.  erotic,  subject  to  womanish  complaints. 
But  this  is  opposed  to  chastity.  Therefore  effeminacy  is 
not  a  vice  opposed  to  perseverance. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vii.  7)  that 
delicacy  is  a  kind  of  effeminacy.  But  to  be  delicate  seems 
akin  to  intemperance.  Therefore  effeminacy  is  not  opposed 
to  perseverance  but  to  temperance. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  Philosopher  says  (ibid.)  that  the 
man  who  is  fond  of  amusement  is  effeminate.  Now  im- 
moderate fondness  of  amusement  is  opposed  to  evrpaireXLa, 
which  is  the  virtue  about  pleasures  of  play,  as  stated  in 
Ethic,  iv.  8.  Therefore  effeminacy  is  not  opposed  to  perse- 
verance. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  vii.  7)  that 
the  persevering  man  is  opposed  to  the  effeminate. 

*  Mollities,  literally  softness. 
326 


327  EFFEMINACY  Q.  138.  Art.  i 

1  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (O.  CXXXVIL,  AA.  1,  2), 
perseverance  is  deserving  of  praise  because  thereby  a  man 
does  not  forsake  a  good  on  account  of  long  endurance  of 
difficulties  and  toils:  and  it  is  directly  opposed  to  this, 
seemingly,  for  a  man  to  be  ready  to  forsake  a  good  on  account 
of  difficulties  which  he  cannot  endure.  This  is  what  we 
understand  by  effeminacy,  because  a  thing  is  said  to  be 
soft  if  it  readily  yields  to  the  touch.  Now  a  thing  is  not 
declared  to  be  soft  through  yielding  to  a  heavy  blow,  for 
walls  yield  to  the  battering-ram.  Wherefore  a  man  is  not 
said  to  be  effeminate  if  he  yields  to  heavy  blows.  Hence 
the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vii.  7)  that  it  is  no  wonder,  if 
a  person  is  overcome  by  strong  and  overwhelming  pleasures 
or  sorrows;  but  he  is  to  be  pardoned  if  he  struggles  against 
them.  Now  it  is  evident  that  fear  of  danger  is  more  impel- 
ling than  the  desire  of  pleasure:  wherefore  Tully  says 
(De  Offic.  i.)  under  the  heading  True  magnanimity  consists 
of  two  things:  It  is  inconsistent  for  one  who  is  not  cast  down 
by  fear,  to  be  defeated  by  lust,  or  who  has  proved  himself 
unbeaten  by  toil,  to  yield  to  pleasure.  Moreover,  pleasure 
itself  is  a  stronger  motive  of  attraction  than  sorrow,  for  the 
lack  of  pleasure  is  a  motive  of  withdrawal,  since  lack  of 
pleasure  is  a  pure  privation.  Wherefore,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  (loc.  cit.).  properly  speaking  an  effeminate  man  is 
one  whc  withdraws  from  good  on  account  of  sorrow  caused 
by  lack  of  pleasure,  yielding  as  it  were  to  a  weak  motion. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  effeminacy  is  caused  in  two  ways. 
In  one  way,  by  custom :  for  where  a  man  is  accustomed  to 
enjoy  pleasures,  it  is  more  difficult  for  him  to  endure  the 
lack  of  them.  In  another  way,  by  natural  disposition, 
because,  to  wit,  his  mind  is  less  persevering  through  the 
frailty  of  his  temperament.  This  is  how  women  are  com- 
pared to  men,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vii.,  loc.  cit.): 
wherefore  those  who  are  subject  to  womanish  complaints 
are  said  to  be  effeminate,  being  womanish  themselves,  as  it 
were. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Toil  is  opposed  to  bodily  pleasure :  wherefore 
it  is  only  toilsome  things  that  are  a  hindrance  to  pleasures. 


Q.  138.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  328 

Now  the  delicate  are  those  who  cannot  endure  toils,  nor 
anything  that  diminishes  pleasure.  Hence  it  is  written 
(Deut.  xxviii.  56) :  The  tender  and  delicate  woman,  that  could 
not  go  upon  the  ground,  nor  set  down  her  foot  for  .  .  .  softness 
(Douay, — niceness).  Thus  delicacy  is  a  kind  of  effeminacy. 
But  properly  speaking  effeminacy  regards  lack  of  pleasures, 
while  delicacy  regards  the  cause  that  hinders  pleasure,  for 
instance  toil  or  the  like. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  play  two  things  may  be  considered. 
In  the  first  place  there  is  the  pleasure,  and  thus  inordinate 
fondness  of  play  is  opposed  to  evrpaireXia.  Secondly, 
we  may  consider  the  relaxation  or  rest  which  is  opposed  to 
toil.  Accordingly  just  as  it  belongs  to  effeminacy  to  be 
unable  to  endure  toilsome  things,  so  too  it  belongs  thereto 
to  desire  play  or  any  other  relaxation  inordinately. 

Second  Article, 
whether  pertinacity  is  opposed  to  perseverance  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — ■ 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  pertinacity  is  not  opposed  to 
perseverance.  For  Gregory  says  (Moral,  xxxi.)  than  perti- 
nacity arises  from  vainglory.  But  vainglory  is  not  opposed 
to  perseverance  but  to  magnanimity,  as  stated  above 
(O.  CXXXIL,  A.  2).  Therefore  pertinacity  is  not  apposed 
to  perseverance. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  If  it  is  opposed  to  perseverance,  this  is  so 
either  by  excess  or  by  deficiency.  Now  it  is  not  opposed  by 
excess :  because  the  pertinacious  also  yield  to  certain  pleasure 
and  sorrow,  since  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  vii.  9) 
they  rejoice  when  they  prevail,  and  grieve  when  their  opinions 
are  rejected.  And  if  it  be  opposed  by  deficiency,  it  will  be 
the  same  as  effeminacy,  which  is  clearly  false.  Therefore 
pertinacity  is  nowise  opposed  to  perseverance. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Just  as  the  persevering  man  persists 
in  good  against  sorrow,  so  too  do  the  continent  and  the 
temperate  against  pleasures,  the  brave  against  fear,  and 
the  meek  against  anger.     Bwt  pertinacity  is  over-persistence 


329  PERTINACITY  Q.  138.  Art.  2 

in  something.  Therefore  pertinacity  is  not  opposed  to 
perseverance  more  than  to  other  virtues. 

On  the  contrary,  Tully  says  (De  Inv.  Rhet.  ii.)  that  perti- 
nacity is  to  perseverance  as  superstition  is  to  religion.  But 
superstition  is  opposed  to  religion,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XCII., 
A.  1).     Therefore  pertinacity  is  opposed  to  perseverance. 

I  answer  that,  As  Isidore  says  (Etym.  x.)  a  person  is  said  to 
be  pertinacious  who  holds  on  impudently,  as  being  utterly 
tenacious.  Pervicacious  has  the  same  meaning,  for  it  sig- 
nifies that  a  man  perseveres  in  his  purpose  until  he  is  vic- 
torious :  for  the  ancients  called  '  vicia '  what  we  call  victory. 
These  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  vii.  9)  calls  lacxpoyvoo/xoves, 
that  is  head-strong,  or  IStoyvfofioves,  that  is  self-opinionated, 
because  they  abide  by  their  opinions  more  than  they 
should;  whereas  the  effeminate  man  does  so  less  than  he 
ought,  and  the  persevering  man,  as  he  ought.  Hence  it  is 
clear  that  perseverance  is  commended  for  observing  the 
mean,  while  pertinacity  is  reproved  for  exceeding  the  mean, 
and  effeminacy  for  falling  short  of  it. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  reason  why  a  man  is  too  persistent 
in  his  own  opinion,  is  that  he  wishes  by  this  means  to  make 
a  show  of  his  own  excellence :  wherefore  this  is  the  result  of 
vainglory  as  its  cause.  Now  it  has  been  stated  above 
(Q.  CXXVII.,  A.  2,  ad  1:  Q.  CXXXIII.,  A.  2),  that  opposi- 
tion of  vices  to  virtues  depends,  not  on  their  cause,  but  on 
their  species. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  pertinacious  man  exceeds  by  persisting 
inordinately  in  something  against  many  difficulties:  yet  he 
takes  a  certain  pleasure  in  the  end,  just  as  the  brave  and  the 
persevering  man.  Since,  however,  this  pleasure  is  sinful, 
seeing  that  he  desires  it  too  much,  and  shuns  the  contrary 
pain,  he  is  like  the  incontinent  or  effeminate  man. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Although  the  other  virtues  persist  against 
the  onslaught  of  the  passions,  they  are  not  commended 
for  persisting  in  the  same  way  as  perseverance  is.  As  to 
continence,  its  claim  to  praise  seems  to  lie  rather  in  over- 
coming pleasures.  Hence  pertinacity  is  directly  opposed 
to  perseverance. 


QUESTION  CXXXIX. 

OF  THE  GIFT  OF  FORTITUDE. 
(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  next  consider  the  gift  corresponding  to  fortitude, 
and  this  is  the  gift  of  fortitude.  Under  this  head  there  are 
two  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  fortitude  is  a  gift  ? 
(2)  Which  among  the  beatitudes  and  fruits  correspond 
to  it? 

First  Article, 
whether  fortitude  is  a  gift  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fortitude  is  not  a  gift.  For  the 
virtues  differ  from  the  gifts :  and  fortitude  is  a  virtue.  There- 
fore it  should  not  be  reckoned  a  gift. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  acts  of  the  gifts  remain  in  heaven, 
as  stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  LXVIIL,  A.  6).  But  the  act  of 
fortitude  does  not  remain  in  heaven:  for  Gregory  says 
(Moral,  i.)  that  fortitude  encourages  the  fainthearted  against 
hardships,  which  will  be  altogether  absent  from  heaven.  There- 
fore fortitude  is  not  a  gift. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  (De  Doctr.  Christ,  ii.) 
that  it  is  a  sign  of  fortitude  to  cut  oneself  adrift  from  all  the 
deadly  pleasures  of  the  passing  show.  Now  noisome  pleasures 
and  delights  are  the  concern  of  temperance  rather  than  of 
fortitude.  Therefore  it  seems  that  fortitude  is  not  the  gift 
corresponding  to  the  virtue  of  fortitude. 

On  the  contrary,  Fortitude  is  reckoned  among  the  other 
gifts  of  the  Holy  Ghost  (Isa.  xi.  2). 

/  answer  that,  Fortitude  denotes  a  certain  firmness  of 

330 


331  GIFT  OF  FORTITUDE         Q.  139.  Art.  i 

mind,  as  stated  above  (O.  CXXIIL,  A.  2:  I.-IL,  Q.  LXI., 
A.  3):  and  this  firmness  of  mind  is  required  both  in  doing 
good  and  in  enduring  evil,  especially  with  regard  to  goods 
or  evils  that  are  difficult.  Now  man,  according  to  his 
proper  and  connatural  mode,  is  able  to  have  this  firmness 
in  both  these  respects,  so  as  not  to  forsake  the  good  on 
account  of  difficulties,  whether  in  accomplishing  an  arduous 
work,  or  in  enduring  grievous  evil.  In  this  sense  fortitude 
denotes  a  special  or  general  virtue,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  CXXIIL,  A.  2). 

Yet  furthermore  man's  mind  is  moved  by  the  Holy  Ghost, 
in  order  that  he  may  attain  the  end  of  each  work  begun, 
and  avoid  whatever  perils  may  threaten.  This  surpasses 
human  nature :  for  sometimes  it  is  not  in  a  man's  power  to 
attain  the  end  of  his  work,  or  to  avoid  evils  or  dangers,  since 
these  may  happen  to  overwhelm  him  in  death.  But  the 
Holy  Ghost  works  this  in  man,  by  bringing  him  to  everlasting 
life,  which  is  the  end  of  all  good  deeds,  and  the  release  from 
all  perils.  A  certain  confidence  of  this  is  infused  into  the 
mind  by  the  Holy  Ghost  Who  expels  any  fear  of  the  contrary. 
It  is  in  this  sense  that  fortitude  is  reckoned  a  gift  of  the  Holy 
Ghost.  For  it  has  been  stated  above  (I.-IL,  Q.  LXVIIL, 
AA.  1,  2)  that  the  gifts  regard  the  motion  of  the  mind  by 
the  Holy  Ghost. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Fortitude,  as  a  virtue,  perfects  the  mind 
in  the  endurance  of  all  perils  whatever;  but  it  does  not  go 
so  far  as  to  give  confidence  of  overcoming  all  dangers :  this 
belongs  to  the  fortitude  that  is  a  gift  of  the  Holy  Ghost. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  gifts  have  not  the  same  acts  in  heaven 
as  on  the  way:  for  there  they  exercise  acts  in  connexion 
with  the  enjoyment  of  the  end.  Hence  the  act  of  fortitude 
there  is  to  enjoy  full  security  from  toil  and  evil. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  gift  of  fortitude  regards  the  virtue  of 
fortitude  not  only  because  it  consists  in  enduring  dangers, 
but  also  inasmuch  as  it  consists  in  accomplishing  any 
difficult  work.  Wherefore  the  gift  of  fortitude  is  directed 
by  the  gift  of  counsel,  which  seems  to  be  concerned  chiefly 
with  the  greater  goods. 


Q.  139.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  332 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  fourth  beatitude:  'blessed  are  they 
that  hunger  and  thirst  after  justice,'  corre- 
sponds to  the  gift  of  fortitude  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  fourth  beatitude,  Blessed 
are  they  that  hunger  and  thirst  after  justice,  does  not  corre- 
spond to  the  gift  of  fortitude.  For  the  gift  of  piety  and  not 
the  gift  of  fortitude  corresponds  to  the  virtue  of  justice. 
Now  hungering  and  thirsting  after  justice  pertain  to  the 
act  of  justice.  Therefore  this  beatitude  corresponds  to 
the  gift  of  piety  rather  than  to  the  gift  of  fortitude. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Hunger  and  thirst  after  justice  imply  a 
desire  for  good.  Now  this  belongs  properly  to  charity,  to 
which  the  gift  of  wisdom,  and  not  the  gift  of  fortitude, 
corresponds,  as  stated  above  (0.  XLV.).  Therefore  this 
beatitude  corresponds,  not  to  the  gift  of  fortitude,  but  to 
the  gift  of  wisdom. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  The  fruits  are  consequent  upon  the 
beatitudes,  since  delight  is  essential  to  beatitude,  according 
to  Ethic,  i.  8.  Now  the  fruits,  apparently,  include  none 
pertaining  to  fortitude.  Therefore  neither  does  any  beati- 
tude correspond  to  it. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Semi.  Dom.  in 
Monte  i.):  Fortitude  becomes  the  hungry  and  thirsty:  since 
those  who  desire  to  enjoy  true  goods,  and  wish  to  avoid  loving 
earthly  and  material  things,  must  toil. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXI.,  A.  2),  Augustine 
makes  the  beatitudes  correspond  to  the  gifts  according  to 
the  order  in  which  they  are  set  forth,  observing  at  the  same 
time  a  certain  fittingness  between  them.  Wherefore  he 
ascribes  the  fourth  beatitude,  concerning  the  hunger  and 
thirst  for  justice,  to  the  fourth  gift,  namely  fortitude. 

Yet  there  is  a  certain  congruity  between  them,  because, 
as  stated  (A.  1),  fortitude  is  about  difficult  things.  Now  it 
is  very  difficult,  not  merely  to  do  virtuous  deeds,  which 


333  GIFT  OF  FORTITUDE  Q.  139-  Art.  2 

receive  the  common  designation  of  works  of  justice,  but 
furthermore  to  do  them  with  an  unsatiable  desire,  which 
may  be  signified  by  hunger  and  thirst  for  justice. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  As  Chrysostom  says  (Horn.  xv.  in  Matth.), 
we  may  understand  here  not  only  particular,  but  also 
universal  justice,  which  is  related  to  all  virtuous  deeds 
according  to  Ethic,  v.  1,  wherein  whatever  is  hard  is  the 
object  of  that  fortitude  which  is  a  gift. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Charity  is  the  root  of  all  the  virtues  and 
gilts,  as  stated  above  (O.  XXIII.,  A.  8,  ad  3:  I. -II., 
0.  LXVIII.,  A.  4,  ad  3).  Hence  whatever  pertains  to  for- 
titude may  also  be  referred  to  charity. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  There  are  two  of  the  fruits  which  correspond 
sufficiently  to  the  gift  of  fortitude:  namely,  patience,  which 
regards  the  enduring  of  evils;  and  longanimity,  which  may 
regard  the  long  delay  and  accomplishment  of  goods. 


QUESTION  CXL. 

OF  THE  PRECEPTS  OF  FORTITUDE. 
(In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  next  consider  the  precepts  of  fortitude:  (i)  The 
precepts  of  fortitude  itself;  (2)  The  precepts  of  its  parts. 

First  Article. 

whether  the  precepts  of  fortitude  are  suitably 
given  in  the  divine  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — ■ 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  precepts  of  fortitude  are 
not  suitably  given  in  the  Divine  Law.  For  the  New  Law 
is  more  perfect  than  the  Old  Law.  Yet  the  Old  Law  contains 
precepts  of  fortitude  (Deut.  xx.).  Therefore  precepts  of 
fortitude  should  have  been  given  in  the  New  Law  also. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Affirmative  precepts  are  of  greater 
import  than  negative  precepts,  since  the  affirmative  include 
the  negative,  but  not  vice  versa.  Therefore  it  is  unsuitable 
for  the  Divine  Law  to  contain  none  but  negative  precepts 
in  prohibition  of  fear. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Fortitude  is  one  of  the  principal  virtues, 
as  stated  above  (O.  CXXIII.,  A.  2:  I.-IL,  Q.  LXL,  A.  2). 
Now  the  precepts  are  directed  to  the  virtues  as  to  their  end : 
wherefore  they  should  be  proportionate  to  them.  There- 
fore the  precepts  of  fortitude  should  have  been  placed 
among  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue,  which  are  the  chief 
precepts  of  the  Law. 

On  the  contrary,  stands  Holy  Writ  which  contains  these 
precepts. 

334 


335  PRECEPTS  OF  FORTITUDE     Q.  140.  Art.  i 

/  answer  that,  Precepts  of  law  are  directed  to  the  end 
intended  by  the  lawgiver.  Wherefore  precepts  of  law  must 
needs  be  framed  in  various  ways  according  to  the  various 
ends  intended  by  lawgivers,  so  that  even  in  human  affairs 
there  are  laws  of  democracies,  others  of  kingdoms,  and 
others  again  of  tyrannical  governments.  Now  the  end  of 
the  Divine  Law  is  that  man  may  adhere  to  God:  where- 
fore the  Divine  Law  contains  precepts  both  of  fortitude  and 
of  the  other  virtues,  with  a  view  to  directing  the  mind  to 
God.  For  this  reason  it  is  written  (Deut.  xx.  3,  4):  Fear  ye 
them  not :  because  the  Lord  your  God  is  in  the  midst  of  you, 
and  will  fight  for  you  against  your  enemies. 

As  to  human  laws,  they  are  directed  to  certain  earthly 
goods,  and  among  them  we  find  precepts  of  fortitude  accord- 
ing to  the  requirements  of  those  goods. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  Old  Testament  contained  temporal 
promises,  while  the  promises  of  the  New  Testament  are 
spiritual  and  eternal,  according  to  Augustine  (Contra 
Faust,  iv.).  Hence  in  the  Old  Law  there  was  need  for  the 
people  to  be  taught  how  to  fight,  even  in  a  bodily  contest, 
in  order  to  obtain  an  earthly  possession.  But  in  the  New 
Testament  men  were  to  be  taught  how  to  come  to  the  posses- 
sion of  eternal  life  by  fighting  spiritually,  according  to 
Matth.  xi.  12,  The  kingdom  of  heaven  suffer eth  violence,  and 
the  violent  bear  it  away.  Hence  Peter  commands  (1  Pet. 
v.  8,  9) :  Your  adversary  the  devil,  as  a  roaring  lion,  goeth 
about,  seeking  whom  he  may  devour:  whom  resist  ye,  strong  in 
faith,  as  also  James  (iv.  7) :  Resist  the  devil,  and  he  will  fly 
from  you.  Since,  however,  men  while  tending  to  spiritual 
goods  may  be  withdrawn  from  them  by  corporal  dangers, 
precepts  of  fortitude  had  to  be  given  even  in  the  New  Law, 
that  they  might  bravely  endure  temporal  evils,  according 
to  Matth.  x.  28,  Fear  ye  not  them  that  kill  the  body. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  law  gives  general  directions  in  its 
precepts.  But  the  things  that  have  to  be  done  in  cases  of 
danger  are  not,  like  the  things  to  be  avoided,  reducible  to 
some  common  good.  Hence  the  precepts  of  fortitude  are 
negative  rather  than  affirmative. 


Q.  140.  Art.  2     THE  "  SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  "  336 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  above  (Q.  CXXIL,  A.  1),  the 
precepts  of  the  decalogue  are  placed  in  the  Law,  as  first 
principles,  which  need  to  be  known  to  all  from  the  outset. 
Wherefore  the  precepts  of  the  decalogue  had  to  be  chiefly 
about  those  acts  of  justice  in  which  the  notion  of  duty  is 
manifest,  and  not  about  acts  of  fortitude,  because  it  is  not 
so  evident  that  it  is  a  duty  for  a  person  not  to  fear  dangers 
of  death. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  precepts  of  the  parts  of  fortitude 
are  suitably  given  in  the  divine  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  precepts  of  the  parts  of 
fortitude  are  unsuitably  given  in  the  Divine  Law.  For  just 
as  patience  and  perseverance  are  parts  of  fortitude,  so  also 
are  magnificence,  magnanimity,  and  confidence,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  CXXVIII.).  Now  we  find  precepts  of  patience 
in  the  Divine  Law,  as  also  of  perseverance.  Therefore 
there  should  also  have  been  precepts  of  magnificence  and 
magnanimity. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Patience  is  a  very  necessary  virtue,  since 
it  is  the  guardian  of  the  other  virtues,  as  Gregory  says 
(Horn,  in  Ev.  xxxv.).  Now  the  other  virtues  are  com- 
manded absolutely.  Therefore  patience  should  not  have 
been  commanded  merely,  as  Augustine  says  (De  Serm. 
Dom.  in  Monte  i.),  as  to  the  preparedness  of  the  mind. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Patience  and  perseverance  are  parts  of 
fortitude,  as  stated  above  (O.  CXXVIII:  Q.  CXXXVI.,  A.  4: 
Q.  CXXXVIL,  A.  2).  Now  the  precepts  of  fortitude  are 
not  affirmative  but  only  negative,  as  stated  above  (A.  1,  ad  2). 
Therefore  the  precepts  of  patience  and  perseverance  should 
have  been  negative  and  not  affirmative. 

The  contrary,  however,  follows  from  the  way  in  which 
they  are  given  by  Holy  Writ. 

I  answer  that,  The  Divine  Law  instructs  man  perfectly 
about  such  things  as  are  necessary  for  right  living.  Now 
in  order  to  live  aright  man  needs  not  only  the  principal 


337  PRECEPTS  OF  FORTITUDE     Q.  i4o.Art.2 

virtues,  but  also  the  secondary  and  annexed  virtues.  Where- 
fore the  Divine  Law  contains  precepts  not  only  about  the 
acts  of  the  principal  virtues,  but  also  about  the  acts  of  the 
secondary  and  annexed  virtues. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Magnificence  and  magnanimity  do  not 
belong  to  the  genus  of  fortitude,  except  by  reason  of  a 
certain  excellence  of  greatness  which  they  regard  in  their 
respective  matters.  Now  things  pertaining  to  excellence 
come  under  the  counsels  of  perfection  rather  than  under  pre- 
cepts of  obligation.  Wherefore,  there  was  need  of  counsels, 
rather  than  of  precepts  about  magnificence  and  magna- 
nimity. On  the  other  hand,  the  hardships  and  toils  of  the 
present  life  pertain  to  patience  and  perseverance,  not  by 
reason  of  any  greatness  observable  in  them,  but  on  account 
of  the  very  nature  of  those  virtues.  Hence  the  need  of 
precepts  of  patience  and  perseverance. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  stated  above  (Q.  III.,  A.  2),  although 
affirmative  precepts  are  always  binding,  they  are  not 
binding  for  always,  but  according  to  place  and  time.  Where- 
fore just  as  the  affirmative  precepts  about  the  other  virtues 
are  to  be  understood  as  to  the  preparedness  of  the  mind, 
in  the  sense  that  man  be  prepared  to  fulfil  them  when 
necessary,  so  too  are  the  precepts  of  patience  to  be  under- 
stood in  the  same  way. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Fortitude,  as  distinct  from  patience  and 
perseverance,  is  about  the  greatest  dangers  wherein  one 
must  proceed  with  caution;  nor  is  it  necessary  to  determine 
what  is  to  be  done  in  particular.  On  the  other  hand, 
patience  and  perseverance  are  about  minor  hardships  and 
toils,  wherefore  there  is  less  danger  in  determining,  especially 
in  general,  what  is  to  be  done  in  such  cases. 


Printed  in  England 


The  "Summa  Theologica"  of 
St.  Thomas  Aquinas,  in  English 

Edited  by  THE   DOMINICAN    FATHERS 


Demy  Svo.  Volumes.     Cloth. 
FIRST  PART. 
QQ.  i-  26     Of  God  and  the  Divine  Attributes. 
27-  49     The  Blessed  Trinity — The  Creation. 
50-  74     The  Angels — The  Work  of  Six  Days. 
75-  94     Treatise  on   Man. 
95-119     On    Man    {continued) — The     Divine 
Government. 


Revised 
Editions  Ready. 

Revised  Editions 
Preparing. 


SECOND  PART.     (Prima  Secunda .) 

QQ.  1-  48     The  End  of  Man — Human  Acts — Passions.  [Ready. 

49-  89     Habits — Virtues  and  Vices.  [Ready. 

90-114     Law  and  Grace.  [Ready- 

SECOND  PART.     {Secunda  Secunda.) 

QQ.  I-  46     Faith,  Hope,  and  Charity.  [Ready. 

47-  79     Prudence — Justice.  [Ready. 

80-100     Justice  {continued) — The  Interior   and  Exterior  Acts 

of  Religion.  [Ready- 

101-140     Piety,  Observance,  and  Contrary  Vices — Fortitude. 

[Ready. 

141- 1 70  Temperance,  its  Integral,  Subjective  and  Potential 
Parts,  and  Contrary  Vices.  [Ready. 

171-189  Gratuitous  Graces — Active  and  Contemplative  Life 
— States  of  Life.  [Ready. 

THIRD  PART  AND  SUPPLEMENT. 

QQ.  1-  26     The  Incarnation.  [Ready. 

27-  59     The  Christology  (including  St.  Thomas's  Mariology). 

[Ready. 

60-  83     The  Sacraments  in  General — Baptism — Confirmation 

— Holy  Eucharist.  [Ready. 

84-Supp.  33     Penance  (including  last  seven  questions  of   the  Third 

Part) — Extreme  Unction.  [Ready. 

34-  68      Holy  Orders — Matrimony.  [Nearly  Ready. 

69-  86      Treatise  on  the  Last  Things.  [Ready. 

87-  99      Purgatory.  [Nearly  Ready. 

Orders  for  the  entire  work  are  received.     Forthcoming  Volumes  will  be  charged  as 

they  appear. 


BURNS    OATES   &    WASHBOURNE    LTD. 

28   ORCHARD   STREET  8-10   PATERNOSTER   ROW 

VV.  1  LONDON  E.C.  4 

BENZIGER    BROTHERS     -       -       NEW    YORK,    CINCINNATI,   CHICAGO 


IINDING  LIST   JUN  15  1938 


University  oi  Toronto 
Library 


DO  NOT 

REMOVE 

THE 

CARD 

FROM 

THIS 

POCKET 


Acme  Library  Card  Pocket 
LOWE-MARTIN  CO.  LIMITED 


W* 


1 


isMi 


s 


m 


RfflS 


selfi 


M 


.  .   ■ '  .