Skip to main content

Full text of "The "Summa theologica" of St. Thomas Aquinas"

See other formats


■  'f  r  .V." .- ,    >  V." 


■'.''.<•>'■ 


'>;<-  '!•■' ' 


:.\X^ 


fi;U.v.O   tAi>A-^.. 


vGyrtvw 


^^mm^^ 


y?Ss^5S 


^VA^HJtt   o  ujvujL 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2010  with  funding  from 

Boston  Library  Consortium  Member  Libraries 


http://www.archive.org/details/summatheologicao211thom 


THE  "SUMMA  THEOLOGICA  " 


Fr.  INNOCENTIUS  APAP.,  O.P.,  S.T.M., 

Censor  Theol. 

EDUS.  CANONICUS  SURMONT. 

ViCARius  Generalis. 

Westmonasterii. 


APPROBATIO  ORDINIS. 

Fr.  VINCENTIUS  McNABB,  O.P.,  S.T.B.. 
Fr.  W.  LEO  MOORE.  O.P.,  S.T.L. 


imprimatttt. 

Fr.  HUMBERTUS  EVEREST,  O.P..  S.T.B., 

Prior  Provincialis  Anglic. 

In  Festo  S.  p.  Dominici, 

die  4  Aug.,  1914. 


THE 

"SUMMA  THEOLOGICA 

OF 

ST.  THOMAS  AQUINAS 

PART  II. 
{FIRST  PART) 


)} 


LITERALLY    TRANSLATED     BY 


FATHERS  OF  THE  ENGLISH  DOMINICAN 

PROVINCE 


FIRST     NUMBER 
(QQ.   I._XLV1II.) 


R.  &  T.  WASHBOURNE,  LTD. 
PATERNOSTER   ROW,  LONDON 

AND  AT  MANCHESTER,  BIRMINGHAM,  AND  GLASGOW 
BENZIGER    BROTHERS  :    NEW    YORK,    CINCINNATI,    CHICAGO 

I9I4 

[All r:ghis  reserved] 


9?)  45^ 


2,/// 


CONTENTS 


TREATISE  ON  THE  LAST  END 

QUESTION  PA(;E 

I.   OF  man's  last  end         -              -              -              -  -  I 

II.    OF  THOSE  THINGS  IN  WHICH  man's  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS  -  1 7 

III.  WHAT    IS    HAPPINESS  ?         -  -  -  -  "34 

IV.  WHAT    THINGS    ARE    REgUIRED    FOR    HAPPINESS  ?  "  5^ 
V.    HOW   IS    HAPPINESS    ATTAINED  ?                      -                  -  -  69 


TREATISE  ON  HUMAN  ACTS 
I.  Of  those  Acts  which  are  Proper  to  Man 

[a)   The  Nature  of  Voluntary  acts  in  General 

VI.    OF    VOLUNTARINESS    AND    INVOLUNTARINESS  -  -  86 

VII.    OF    THE    CIRCUMSTANCES    OF    HUMAN    ACTS  -  -  IO4 

VIII.    OF    THE    OBJECT    OF    VOLITION        -                   -  -  -  II3 

IX.    WHAT    MOVES    THE    WILL  ?                  -                   -  -  -  I20 

X.    HOW    IS    THE    WILL    MOVED  ?             -                   -  -  _  133 

{b)   The  Nature  of  Elicited  Voluntary  Acts 

XI.  OF    ENJOYMENT  OR    FRUITION         -                   -                   -                   -       142 

XII.  OF    INTENTION  __----       15c 

XIII.  OF    CHOICE  _._---       158 

XIV.  OF    COUNSEL  -  -                  -                   -                  -                  -1 69 

XV.  OF    CONSENT  -                   -                   -                   -                   -                   -1 79 

XVI.    OF    USE      -------       186 

(c)   The  Nature  of  Commanded   Voluntary  Acts 

XVII.    OF  THE  ACTS  WHICH  ARE  COMMANDED  BY  THE  WILL  -       I93 

[d]   The  Division  of  Human  Acts 

XVIIl.    OF     THE     GOODNESS     AND     MALICE     OF     HUMAN     ACTS     IN 

GENERAL  -  -  -  -  -  -21  () 

XIX.    OF  THE  GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  OF  THE  INTERIOR  ACT   OF 

THE    WILL  -  -  -  -  -  -       -33 

V 


vi  CONTENTS 

QUESTION.  PAGE 

XX.    OF  THE  GOODNESS  AND  MALICE   OF   EXTERNAL  HUMAN 

ACTS  _-----       256 

XXI.    OF  THE   CONSEQUENCES    OF  GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  IN 

HUMAN  ACTS  -  _  _  -  -       268 


2.  Of  the  Passions,  which  are  Acts  common  to 
Man  and  other  Animals 

{a)  In  General 

XXII.  OF  the  subject  of  the  soul's  passions    -             -  277 

XXIII.  OF  the  different  kinds  of  passions         -             -  284 

,^    XXIV.  OF  good  and  evil  in  the  passions  of  the  soul  -  293 

XXV.  OF  THE  order  OF  THE  PASSIONS  TO  ONE  ANOTHER  3OI 

{b)  In  Particular 

XXVI.    OF  THE  CONCUPISCIBLE  PASSIONS   AND   FIRST  OF  LOVE  3 II 

XXVII.    OF    THE    CAUSE    OF   LOVE  -  -  -  "319 

XXVIII.    OF   THE    EFFECTS    OF    LOVE        -                  -                  -                  -  326 

XXIX.    OF    HATRED        -'                -                  -                  -                  -                  "  33^ 

XXX.    OF    CONCUPISCENCE    OR    DESIRE                -                  -                  -  348 

XXXI.    OF   DELIGHT    OR    PLEASURE        -                  -                  -                  -  356 

XXXII.    OF    THE    CAUSE    OF    PLEASURE                    _                  -                  -  372 

XXXIII.  OF   THE    EFFECTS    OF    PLEASURE               -                  -                  -  387 

XXXIV.  OF   THE    GOODNESS    AND    MALICE    OF    PLEASURES             -  395 
XXXV.    OF    SORROW    OR    PAIN                      _                  -                  -                  -  404 

XXXVI.    OF   THE    CAUSES    OF    SORROW    OR    PAIN                  -                  -  424 

XXXVII.    OF   THE    EFFECTS    OF   SORROW    OR    PAIN                -                  -  432 

XXXVIII.    OF    THE    REMEDIES  OF    SORROW    OR    PAIN             -                  -  44O 

XXXIX.    OF    THE    GOODNESS    OR    MALICE    OF    SORROW    OR    PAIN  448 

XL.    OF    THE     IRASCIBLE     PASSIONS     AND     FIRST     OF     HOPE 

AND    DESPAIR                  -----  455 

XLI.    OF   FEAR               ------  468 

XLII.    OF    THE    OBJECT    OF    FEAR           -                  -                  -                  -  476 

XLIII.    OF    THE    CAUSE    OF   FEAR             -                  -                  -           *      "  4^7 

XLIV.    OF   THE    EFFECTS    OF   FEAR        -  -  -  "491 

XLV.    OF    DARING        ------  499 

XLVI.    OF    ANGER           ------  507 

XLVII.    OF   THE   EFFECTIVE   CAUSE   AND    OF  THE   REMEDIES    OF 

ANGER                ------  522 

XLVIII.    OF   THE    EFFECTS    OF    ANGER    -                  -                  -                  -  530 


TREATISE  ON  THE  LAST  END 


THE   "SUMMA  THEOLOGIGA" 

FIRST  PART  OF  THE  SECOND  PART. 

PROLOGUE. 

Since,  as  Damascene  states  [De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.),  man  is  said 
to  be  made  to  God's  image,  in  so  far  as  the  image  implies  an 
intelligent  being  endowed  with  free-will  and  self-movement  : 
now  that  we  have  treated  of  the  exemplar,  i.e.,  God,  and  of 
those  things  which  come  forth  from  the  power  of  God  in 
accordance  with  His  will;  it  remains  for  us  to  treat  of  His 
image,  i.e.,  man,  inasmuch  as  he  too  is  the  principle  of  his 
actions,  as  having  free-will  and  control  of  his  actions. 

QUESTION  I. 

OF  MAN'S  LAST  END. 
{In  Eight  Articles.) 

In  this  matter  we  shall  consider  first  the  last  end  of  human 
life ;  and  secondly,  those  things  by  means  of  which  man  may 
advance  towards  this  end,  or  stray  from  the  path:  for  the 
end  is  the  rule  of  whatever  is  ordained  to  the  end.  And 
since  the  last  end  of  human  life  is  stated  to  be  happiness,  we 
must  consider  (i)  the  last  end  in  general;  (2)  Happiness. 

Concerning  the  iirst  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  it  is  fitting  for  man  to  act  for  an  end  ?  (2) 
Whether  this  is  proper  to  the  rational  nature  ?  (3)  Whether 
a  man's  actions  are  specified  by  their  end  ?  (4)  Whether 
there  is  any  last  end  of  human  life  ?  (5)  Whether  one  man 
can  have  several  last  ends  ?     (6)  Whether  man  ordains  all 

II.  I  I 


2  QUESTION  I 

to  the  last  end  ?  (7)  Whether  all  men  have  the  same  last 
end  ?  (8)  Whether  all  other  creatures  concur  with  man  in 
that  last  end  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  it  is  fitting  for  man  to  act  for  an  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  unfitting  for  man  to  act  for  an  end. 
For  a  cause  is  naturally  first.  But  an  end,  in  its  very  name, 
implies  something  that  is  last.  Therefore  an  end  is  not  a 
cause.  But  that  for  which  a  man  acts,  is  the  cause  of  his 
action;  since  this  preposition  for  indicates  a  relation  of 
causality.  Therefore  it  is  not  fitting  for  man  to  act  for  an 
end. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  that  which  is  itself  the  last  end  is  not  for 
an  end.  But  in  some  cases  the  last  end  is  an  action,  as  the 
Philosopher  states  {Ethic,  i.).  Therefore  man  does  not  do 
everything  for  an  end. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  then  does  a  man  seem  to  act  for  an  end, 
when  he  acts  deliberately.  But  man  does  many  things 
without  deliberation,  sometimes  not  even  thinking  of  what 
he  is  doing;  for  instance  when  one  moves  one's  foot  or  hand, 
or  scratches  one's  beard,  while  intent  on  something  else. 
Therefore  man  does  not  do  everything  for  an  end. 

On  the  contrary,  All  things  contained  in  a  genus  are 
derived  from  the  principle  of  that  genus.  Now  the  end  is 
the  principle  in  human  operations,  as  the  Philosopher  states 
[Phys.  ii.).  Therefore  it  is  fitting  for  man  to  do  everything 
for  an  end. 

/  answer  that,  Of  actions  done  by  man  those  alone  are 
properly  called  human,  which  are  proper  to  man  as  man. 
Now  man  differs  from  irrational  animals  in  this,  that  he  is 
master  of  his  actions.  Wherefore  those  actions  alone  are 
properly  called  human,  of  which  man  is  master.  Now  man 
is  master  of  his  actions  through  his  reason  and  will ;  whence, 
too,  the  free-will  is  called  the  faculty  of  will  and  reason. 
Therefore  those  actions  are  properly  called  human,  which 
proceed  from  a  deliberate  will.     And  if  any  other  actions 


MAN'S  LAST  END  3 

befit  man,  they  can  be  called  actions  of  a  man,  but  not 
properly  human  actions,  since  they  are  not  proper  to  man  as 
man. — Now  it  is  clear  that  whatever  actions  proceed  from  a 
power,  are  caused  by  that  power  in  accordance  with  the  nature 
of  its  object.  But  the  object  of  the  will  is  the  end  and  the 
good.     Therefore  all  human  actions  must  be  for  an  end. 

Rej)ly  Ohj.  i.  Although  the  end  be  last  in  the  order  of 
execution,  yet  it  is  first  in  the  order  of  the  agent's  intention. 
And  it  is  in  this  way  that  it  is  a  cause. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  If  any  human  action  be  the  last  end,  it  must 
be  voluntary,  else  it  would  not  be  human,  as  stated  above. 
Now  an  action  is  voluntary  in  one  of  two  ways :  first,  because 
it  is  commanded  by  the  will,  e.g.,  to  walk,  or  to  speak; 
secondly,  because  it  is  elicited  by  the  will,  for  instance  the 
very  act  of  willing.  Now  it  is  impossible  for  the  very  act 
elicited  by  the  will  to  be  the  last  end.  For  the  object  of 
the  will  is  the  end,  just  as  the  object  of  sight  is  colour: 
wherefore  just  as  the  first  visible  cannot  be  the  act  of  seeing, 
because  every  act  of  seeing  is  directed  to  a  visible  object; 
so  the  first  appetible,  i.e.,  the  end,  cannot  be  the  very  act 
of  willing.  Consequently  it  follows  that  if  a  human  action 
be  the  last  end,  it  must  be  an  action  commanded  by  the  will : 
so  that  there,  some  action  of  man,  at  least  the  act  of  willing, 
is  for  the  end.  Therefore  whatever  a  man  does,  it  is  true 
to  say  that  man  acts  for  an  end,  even  when  he  does  that 
action  in  which  the  last  end  consists. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Such  like  actions  are  not  properly  human 
actions;  since  they  do  not  proceed  from  deliberation  of  the 
reason,  which  is  the  proper  principle  of  human  actions. 
Therefore  they  have  indeed  an  imaginary  end,  but  not  one 
that  is  fixed  by  reason. 


QUESTION  I 


Second  Article. 

whether  it  is  proper  to  the  rational  nature 
to  act  for  an  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  it  is  proper  to  the  rational  nature 
to  act  for  an  end.  For  man,  whom  it  befits  to  act  for  an  end, 
never  acts  for  an  unknown  end.  On  the  other  hand,  there 
are  many  things  that  have  no  knowledge  of  an  end;  either 
because  they  are  altogether  without  knowledge,  as  insensible 
creatures :  or  because  they  do  not  apprehend  the  idea  of  an 
end  as  such,  as  irrational  animals.  Therefore  it  seems 
proper  to  the  rational  nature  to  act  for  an  end. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  to  act  for  an  end  is  to  order  one's  action  to 
an  end.  But  this  is  the  work  of  reason.  Therefore  it  does 
not  befit  things  that  lack  reason. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  good  and  the  end  is  the  object  of  the 
will.  But  the  will  is  in  the  reason  {De  Anima  iii.).  There- 
fore to  act  for  an  end  belongs  to  none  but  a  rational  nature. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  proves  [Phys.  ii.)  that 
not  only  mind  but  also  nature  acts  for  an  end. 

I  answer  that,  Every  agent,  of  necessity,  acts  for  an  end. 
For  if,  in  a  number  of  causes  ordained  to  one  another,  the 
first  be  removed,  the  others  must,  of  necessity,  be  removed 
also.  Now  the  first  of  all  causes  is  the  final  cause.  The 
reason  of  which  is  that  matter  does  not  receive  form,  save 
in  so  far  as  it  is  moved  by  an  agent ;  for  nothing  reduces  itself 
from  potentiality  to  act.  But  an  agent  does  not  move 
except  out  of  intention  for  an  end.  For  if  the  agent  were 
not  determinate  to  some  particular  effect,  it  would  not  do 
one  thing  rather  than  another:  consequently  in  order  that 
it  produce  a  determinate  effect,  it  must,  of  necessity,  be 
determined  to  some  certain  one,  which  has  the  nature  of  an 
end.  And  just  as  this  determination  is  effected,  in  the 
rational  nature,  by  the  rational  appetite,  which  is  called  the 
will ;  so,  in  other  things,  it  is  caused  by  their  natural  inclina- 
tion, which  is  called  the  natural  appetite. 


MAN'S  LAST  END  5 

Nevertheless  it  must  be  observed  that  a  thing  tends  to  an 
end,  by  its  own  action  or  movement,  in  two  ways :  first,  as  it 
were,  moving  itself  to  the  end, — as  man ;  secondly,  as  though 
moved  by  another  to  the  end,  as  an  arrow  tends  to  a  deter- 
minate end  through  being  moved  by  the  archer,  who  directs 
his  action  to  the  end.  Therefore  those  things  that  are 
possessed  of  reason,  move  themselves  to  an  end;  because 
they  have  dominion  over  their  actions,  through  their  free- 
will which  is  tlie  faculty  of  will  and  reason.  But  those  things 
that  lack  reason  tend  to  an  end,  by  natural  inclination,  as 
though  moved  by  another  and  not  by  themselves;  since  they 
do  not  know  the  nature  of  an  end  as  such,  and  consequently 
cannot  ordain  anything  to  an  end,  but  can  be  ordained  to 
an  end,  only  by  another.  For  the  entire  irrational  nature 
is  in  comparison  to  God  as  an  instrument  to  the  principal 
agent,  as  stated  above  (L  Q.  XXII.,  A.  2  ad  ^\  Q.  CIIL, 
A.  I  ^i  3).  Consequently  it  is  proper  to  the  rational  nature 
to  tend  to  an  end,  as  though  directing  (agens)  and  leading 
itself  to  the  end :  whereas  it  is  proper  to  the  irrational  nature 
to  tend  to  an  end,  as  directed  or  led  by  another,  whether  it 
apprehend  the  end,  as  do  irrational  animals,  or  do  not 
apprehend  it,  as  is  the  case  of  those  which  are  altogether 
void  of  knowledge. 

Reply  Obf.  i.  When  man  of  himself  acts  for  an  end,  he 
knows  the  end:  but  when  he  is  directed  or  led  by  another, 
for  instance,  when  he  acts  at  another's  command,  or  when 
he  is  moved  under  another's  compulsion,  it  is  not  necessary 
that  he  should  know  the  end.  And  it  is  thus  with  irrational 
creatures. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  To  ordain  towards  an  end  belongs  to  that 
which  directs  itself  to  an  end :  whereas  to  be  ordained  to  an 
end  belongs  to  that  which  is  directed  by  another  to  an  end. 
And  this  can  belong  to  an  irrational  nature,  but  owing  to 
some  one  possessed  of  reason. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  object  of  the  will  is  the  end  and  the  good 
in  universal.  Consequently  there  can  be  no  will  in  those 
things  that  lack  reason  and  intellect,  since  they  cannot 
apprehend  the  universal;  but  they  have  a  natural  appetite 


6  QUESTION  I 

or  a  sensitive  appetite,  determinate  to  some  particular  good. 
Now  it  is  clear  that  particular  causes  are  moved  by  a  uni- 
versal cause:  thus  the  governor  of  a  city,  who  intends  the 
common  good,  moves,  by  his  command,  all  the  particular 
departments  of  the  city.  Consequently  all  things  that  lack 
reason  are,  of  necessity,  moved  to  their  particular  ends  by 
some  rational  will  which  extends  to  the  universal  good, 
namely  by  the  Divine  will. 

Third  Article, 
whether  human  acts  are  specified  by  their  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  human  acts  are  not  specified  by 
their  end.  For  the  end  is  an  extrinsic  cause.  But  every- 
thing is  specified  by  an  intrinsic  principle.  Therefore  human 
acts  are  not  specified  by  their  end. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  that  which  gives  a  thing  its  species  should 
exist  before  it.  But  the  end  comes  into  existence  after- 
wards. Therefore  a  human  act  does  not  derive  its  species 
from  the  end. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  one  thing  cannot  be  in  more  than  one 
species.  But  one  and  the  same  act  may  happen  to  be 
ordained  to  various  ends.  Therefore  the  end  does  not  give 
the  species  to  human  acts. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [De  Mor.  Eccl.  et  Manich. 
ii.) :  According  as  their  end  is  worthy  of  blame  or  fraise,  so  are 
our  deeds  worthy  of  blame  or  praise. 

I  answer  that,  Each  thing  receives  its  species  in  respect 
of  an  act  and  not  in  respect  of  potentiality;  wherefore 
things  composed  of  matter  and  form  are  established  in 
their  respective  species  by  their  own  forms.  And  this  is 
also  to  be  observed  in  proper  movements.  For  since  move- 
ments are,  in  a  way,  divided  into  action  and  passion,  each 
of  these  receives  its  species  from  an  act ;  action  indeed  from 
the  act  which  is  the  principle  of  acting,  and  passion  from  the 
act  which  is  the  terminus  of  the  movement.  Wherefore 
heating,  as  an  action,  is  nothing  else  than  a  certain  move- 


MAN'S  LAST  END  7 

ment  proceeding  from  heat,  while  heating  as  a  passion  is 
nothing  else  than  a  movement  towards  heat:  and  it  is  the 
definition  that  shows  the  specific  nature.  And  either  way, 
human  acts,  whether  they  be  considered  as  actions,  or  as 
passions,  receive  their  species  from  the  end.  For  human 
acts  can  be  considered  in  both  ways,  since  man  moves  him- 
self, and  is  moved  by  himself.  Now  it  has  been  stated  above 
(A.  i)  that  acts  are  called  human,  inasmuch  as  they  proceed 
from  a  deliberate  will.  Now  the  object  of  the  will  is  the 
good  and  the  end.  And  hence  it  is  clear  that  the  principle 
of  human  acts,  in  so  far  as  they  are  human,  is  the  end.  In 
like  manner  it  is  their  terminus :  for  the  human  act  terminates 
at  that  which  the  will  intends  as  the  end;  thus  in  natural 
agents  the  form  of  the  thing  generated  is  conformed  to  the 
form  of  the  generator.  And  since,  as  Ambrose  says  [Prolog, 
super  Luc.)  morality  is  said  properly  of  man,  moral  acts 
properly  speaking  receive  their  species  from  the  end,  for 
moral  acts  are  the  same  as  human  acts. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  end  is  not  altogether  extrinsic  to  the 
act,  because  it  is  related  to  the  act  as  principle  or  terminus; 
and  it  is  just  this  that  is  essential  to  an  act,  viz.,  to  proceed 
from  something,  considered  as  action,  and  to  proceed 
towards  something,  considered  as  passion. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  end,  in  so  far  as  it  pre-exists  in  the 
intention,  pertains  to  the  will,  as  stated  above  (A.  1.  ad  1). 
And  it  is  thus  that  it  gives  the  species  to  the  human  or  moral 
act. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  One  and  the  same  act,  in  so  far  as  it  proceeds 
once  from  the  agent,  is  ordained  to  but  one  proximate  end, 
from  which  it  has  its  species:  but  it  can  be  ordained  to 
several  remote  ends,  of  which  one  is  the  end  of  the  other. 
It  is  possible,  however,  that  an  act  which  is  one  in  respect  of 
its  natural  species,  be  ordained  to  several  ends  of  the  will: 
thus  this  act  to  kill  a  man,  which  is  but  one  act  in  respect  of 
its  natural  species,  can  be  ordained,  as  to  an  end,  to  the  safe- 
guarding of  justice,  and  to  the  satisfying  of  anger:  the  result 
being  that  there  would  be  several  acts  in  different  species  of 
morality :  since  in  one  way  there  will  be  an  act  of  virtue,  in 


8  QUESTION  I 

another,  an  act  of  vice.  For  a  movement  does  not  receive 
its  species  from  that  which  is  its  terminus  accidentally,  but 
only  from  that  which  is  its  per  se  terminus.  Now  moral  ends 
are  accidental  to  a  natural  thing,  and  conversely  the  relation 
to  a  natural  end  is  accidental  to  morality.  Consequently 
there  is  no  reason  why  acts  which  are  the  same  considered 
in  their  natural  species,  should  not  be  diverse,  considered  in 
their  moral  species,  and  conversely. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  there  is  one  last  end  of  human  life  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  is  no  last  end  of  human 
life,  but  that  we  proceed  to  infinity.  For  good  is  essentially 
diffusive,  as  Dionysius  states  (Div.  Norn.  iv.).  Conse- 
quently if  that  which  proceeds  from  good  is  itself  good,  the 
latter  must  needs  diffuse  some  other  good:  so  that  the 
diffusion  of  good  goes  on  indefinitely.  But  good  has  the 
nature  of  an  end.  Therefore  there  is  an  indefinite  series  of 
ends. 

6b j.  2.  Further,  things  pertaining  to  the  reason  can  be 
multiplied  to  infinity :  thus  mathematical  quantities  have  no 
Hmit.  For  the  same  reason  the  species  of  numbers  are  in- 
finite, since,  given  any  number,  the  reason  can  think  of 
one  yet  greater.  But  desire  of  the  end  is  consequent  on  the 
apprehension  of  the  reason.  Therefore  it  seems  that  there 
is  also  an  infinite  series  of  ends. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  good  and  the  end  is  the  object  of  the 
will.  But  the  will  can  react  on  itself  an  infinite  number  of 
times :  for  I  can  will  something,  and  will  to  will  it,  and  so  on 
indefinitely.  Therefore  there  is  an  infinite  series  of  ends 
of  the  human  will,  and  there  is  no  last  end  of  the  human  will. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  [Metaph.  ii.)  that 
to  suppose  a  thing  to  be  indefinite  is  to  deny  that  it  is  good. 
But  the  good  is  that  which  has  the  nature  of  an  end.  There- 
fore it  is  contrary  to  the  nature  of  an  end  to  proceed  in- 
definitely.    Therefore  it  is  necessary  to  fix  one  last  end. 


MAN'S  LAST  END  Q 

/  answer  that,  Absolutely  speaking,  it  is  not  possible  to 
proceed  indefinitely  in  the  matter  of  ends,  from  any  point 
of  view.  For  in  whatsoever  things  there  is  an  essential 
order  of  one  to  another,  if  the  first  be  removed,  those  that 
are  ordained  to  the  first,  must  of  necessity  be  removed  also. 
Wherefore  the  Philosopher  proves  (Phys.  viii.)  that  we 
cannot  proceed  to  infinitude  in  causes  of  movement,  because 
then  there  would  be  no  first  mover,  without  which  neither 
can  the  others  move,  since  they  move  only  through  being 
moved  by  the  first  mover.  Now  there  is  to  be  observed 
a  twofold  order  in  ends, — the  order  of  intention,  and  the 
order  of  execution :  and  in  either  of  these  orders  there  must 
be  something  first.  For  that  which  is  first  in  the  order  of 
intention,  is  the  principle,  as  it  were,  moving  the  appetite; 
consequently,  if  you  remove  this  principle,  there  will  be 
nothing  to  move  the  appetite.  On  the  other  hand,  the 
principle  in  execution  is  that  wherein  operation  has  its 
beginning;  and  if  this  principle  be  taken  away,  no  one  will 
begin  to  work.  Now  the  principle  in  the  intention  is  the 
last  end;  while  the  principle  in  execution  is  the  first  of  the 
things  which  are  ordained  to  the  end.  Consequently,  on 
neither  side  is  it  possible  to  go  on  to  infinity;  since  if  there 
were  no  last  end,  nothing  would  be  desired,  nor  would  any 
action  have  its  term,  nor  would  the  intention  of  the  agent 
be  at  rest ;  while  if  there  is  no  first  thing  among  those  that 
are  ordained  to  the  end,  none  would  begin  to  work  at  any- 
thing, and  counsel  would  have  no  term,  but  would  con- 
tinue indefinitely. 

On  the  other  hand,  nothing  hinders  infinity  from  being 
in  things  that  are  ordained  to  one  another  not  essentially 
but  accidentally;  for  accidental  causes  are  indeterminate. 
And  in  this  way  it  happens  that  there  is  an  accidental 
infinity  of  ends,  and  of  things  ordained  to  the  end. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  very  nature  of  good  is  that  some- 
thing flows  from  it,  but  not  that  it  flows  from  something  else. 
Since,  therefore,  good  has  the  nature  of  end,  and  the  first 
good  is  the  last  end,  this  argument  does  not  prove  that 
there  is  no  last  end;  but  that  from  the  end,  already  sup- 


10  QUESTION  I 

posed,  we  may  proceed  downwards  indefinitely  towards  those 
things  that  are  ordained  to  the  end.  And  this  would  be 
true  if  we  considered  but  the  power  of  the  First  Good,  which 
is  infinite.  But,  since  the  First  Good  diffuses  itself  accord- 
ing to  the  intellect,  to  which  it  is  proper  to  flow  forth  into 
its  effects  according  to  a  certain  fixed  form;  it  follows  that 
there  is  a  certain  measure  to  the  flow  of  good  things  from 
the  First  Good  from  Which  all  other  goods  share  the  power 
of  diffusion.  Consequently  the  diffusion  of  good  does  not 
proceed  indefinitely,  but,  as  it  is  written  (Wisd.  xi.  21), 
God  disposes  all  things  in  number,  weight  and  measure. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  In  things  which  are  of  themselves,  reason 
begins  from  principles  that  are  known  naturally,  and 
advances  to  some  term.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher  proves 
[Poster,  i.)  that  there  is  no  infinite  process  in  demonstrations, 
because  there  we  find  a  process  of  things  having  an  essential, 
not  an  accidental,  connection  with  one  another.  But  in 
those  things  which  are  accidentally  connected,  nothing 
hinders  the  reason  from  proceeding  indefinitely.  Now  it  is 
accidental  to  a  stated  quantity  or  number,  as  such,  that 
quantity  or  unity  be  added  to  it.  Wherefore  in  suchlike 
things  nothing  hinders  the  reason  from  an  indefinite  process. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  multiplication  of  acts  of  the  will 
reacting  on  itself,  is  accidental  to  the  order  of  ends.  This 
is  clear  from  the  fact  that  in  regard  to  one  and  the  same 
end,  the  will  reacts  on  itself  indifferently  once  or  several 
times. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  one  man  can  have  several  last  ends  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  possible  for  one  man's  will  to  be 
directed  at  the  same  time  to  several  things,  as  last  ends. 
For  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei.  xix.)  that  some  held  man's 
last  end  to  consist  in  four  things,  viz.,  in  pleasure,  repose, 
the  gifts  of  nature,  and  virtue.  But  these  are  clearly  more 
than  one  thing.  Therefore  one  man  can  place  the  last  end 
of  his  wiU  in  many  things. 


MAN'S  LAST  END  ii 

Obj.  2.  Further,  things  not  in  opposition  to  one  another 
do  not  exclude  one  another.  Now  there  are  many  things 
which  are  not  in  opposition  to  one  another.  Therefore  the 
supposition  that  one  thing  is  the  last  end  of  the  will  does 
not  exclude  others. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  by  the  fact  that  it  places  its  last  end  in 
one  thing,  the  will  does  not  lose  its  freedom.  But  before  it 
placed  its  last  end  in  that  thing,  e.g.,  pleasure,  it  could 
place  it  in  something  else,  e.g.,  riches.  Therefore  even  after 
having  placed  his  last  end  in  pleasure,  a  man  can  at  the 
same  time  place  his  last  end  in  riches.  Therefore  it  is 
possible  for  one  man's  will  to  be  directed  at  the  same  time 
to  several  things,  as  last  ends. 

On  the  contrary,  That  in  which  a  man  rests  as  in  his  last 
end,  is  master  of  his  affections,  since  he  takes  therefrom  his 
entire  rule  of  life.  Hence  of  gluttons  it  is  written  (Phil, 
iii.  19) :  Whose  god  is  their  belly  :  viz.,  because  they  place 
their  last  end  in  the  pleasures  of  the  belly.  Now  according 
to  Matth.  vi.  24,  No  man  can  serve  two  masters,  such,  namely, 
as  are  not  ordained  to  one  another.  Therefore  it  is  im- 
possible for  one  man  to  have  several  last  ends  not  ordained 
to  one  another. 

/  answer  that,  It  is  impossible  for  one  man's  will  to  be 
directed  at  the  same  time  to  diverse  things,  as  last  ends. 
Three  reasons  may  be  assigned  for  this.  First,  because,  since 
everything  desires  its  own  perfection,  a  man  desires  for 
his  ultimate  end,  that  which  he  desires  as  his  perfect  and 
crowning  good.  Hence  Augustine  says  {De  Civ.  Dei.  xix.) : 
In  sfeaking  of  the  end  of  good  we  mean  now,  not  that  it  passes 
away  so  as  to  be  no  more,  but  that  it  is  perfected  so  as  to  be 
complete.  It  is  therefore  necessary  for  the  last  end  so  to  fill 
man's  appetite,  that  nothing  is  left  beside  it  for  man  to  desire. 
Which  is  not  possible,  if  something  else  be  required  for  his 
perfection.  Consequently  it  is  not  possible  for  the  appetite 
so  to  tend  to  two  things,  as  though  each  were  its  perfect  good. 

The  second  reason  is  because,  just  as  in  the  process  of 
reasoning,  the  principle  is  that  which  is  naturally  known,  so 
in  the  process  of  the  rational  appetite,  i.e.,  the  will,  the 


12  QUESTION  I 

principle  needs  to  be  that  which  is  naturally  desired.  Now 
this  must  needs  be  one:  since  nature  tends  to  one  thing 
only.  But  the  principle  in  the  process  of  the  rational  appe- 
tite is  the  last  end.  Therefore  that  to  which  the  will  tends, 
as  to  its  last  end,  is  one. 

The  third  reason  is  because,  since  voluntary  actions 
receive  their  species  from  the  end,  as  stated  above  (A.  3), 
they  must  needs  receive  their  genus  from  the  last  end,  which 
is  common  to  them  all:  just  as  natural  things  are  placed 
in  a  genus  according  to  a  common  form.  Since,  then,  all 
things  that  can  be  desired  by  the  will,  belong,  as  such,  to 
one  genus,  the  last  end  must  needs  be  one.  And  all  the 
more  because  in  every  genus  there  is  one  first  principle;  and 
the  last  end  has  the  nature  of  a  first  principle,  as  stated 
above.  Now  as  the  last  end  of  man,  simply  as  man,  is  to 
the  whole  human  race,  so  is  the  last  end  of  any  individual 
man  to  that  individual.  Therefore,  just  as  of  all  men  there 
is  naturally  one  last  end,  so  the  will  of  an  individual  man 
must  be  fixed  on  one  last  end. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  All  these  several  objects  were  considered  as 
one  perfect  good  resulting  therefrom,  by  those  who  placed 
in  them  the  last  end. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  it  is  possible  to  find  several  things 
which  are  not  in  opposition  to  one  another,  yet  it  is  con- 
trary to  a  thing's  perfect  good,  that  anything  besides,  be 
required  for  that  thing's  perfection. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  power  of  the  will  does  not  extend  to 
making  opposites  exist  at  the  same  time.  Which  would 
be  the  case  were  it  to  tend  to  several  diverse  objects  as 
last  ends,  as  has  been  shown  above  [ad  2) . 

Sixth  Article. 

WHETHER  MAN  WILLS  ALL,  WHATSOEVER  HE  WILLS,  FOR  THE 

LAST   END  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 
Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  man  does  not  wih  all,  what- 
soever he  wills,  for  the  last  end.     For  things  ordained  to  the 


MAN'S  LAST  END  13 

last  end  are  said  to  be  serious  matter,  as  being  useful.  But 
jests  are  foreign  to  serious  matter.  Therefore  what  man 
does  in  jest,  he  ordains  not  to  the  last  end. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  at  the  beginning 
of  his  Metaphysics  (ii.)  that  speculative  science  is  sought 
for  its  own  sake.  Now  it  cannot  be  said  that  each  specu- 
lative science  is  the  last  end.  Therefore  man  does  not 
desire  all,  whatsoever  he  desires,  for  the  last  end. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  whoever  ordains  something  to  an  end, 
thinks  of  that  end.  But  man  does  not  always  think  of  the 
last  end  in  all  that  he  desires  or  does.  Therefore  man 
neither  desires  nor  does  all  for  the  last  end. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Civ.  Dei.  xix.) :  That 
is  the  end  of  our  good,  for  the  sake  of  which  we  love  other 
things,  whereas  we  love  it  for  its  own  sake. 

I  answer  that,  Man  must,  of  necessity,  desire  all,  whatso- 
ever he  desires,  for  the  last  end.  This  is  evident  for 
two  reasons.  First,  because  whatever  man  desires,  he 
desires  it  under  the  aspect  of  good.  And  if  he  desire  it,  not 
as  his  perfect  good,  which  is  the  last  end,  he  must,  of 
necessity,  desire  it  as  tending  to  the  perfect  good,  because 
the  beginning  of  anything  is  always  ordained  to  its  com- 
pletion; as  is  clearly  the  case  in  effects  both  of  nature  and 
of  art.  Wherefore  every  beginning  of  perfection  is  ordained 
to  complete  perfection  which  is  achieved  through  the  last 
end.  Secondly,  because  the  last  end  stands  in  the  same 
relation  in  moving  the  appetite,  as  the  first  mover  in  other 
movements.  Now  it  is  clear  that  secondary  moving 
causes  do  not  move  save  inasmuch  as  they  are  moved 
by  the  first  mover.  Therefore  secondary  objects  of 
the  appetite  do  not  move  the  appetite,  except  as 
ordained  to  the  first  object  of  the  appetite,  which  is  the 
last  end. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Actions  done  jestingly  are  not  directed  to 
any  external  end;  but  merely  to  the  good  of  the  jester,  in 
so  far  as  they  afford  him  pleasure  or  relaxation.  But  man's 
consummate  good  is  his  last  end. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  same  applies  to  speculative  science; 


14  QUESTION  I 

which  is  desired  as  the  scientist's  good,  included  in  com- 
plete and  perfect  good,  which  is  the  ultimate  end. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  One  need  not  always  be  thinking  of  the 
last  end,  whenever  one  desires  or  does  something:  but  the 
virtue  of  the  first  intention,  which  was  in  respect  of  the 
last  end,  remains  in  every  desire  directed  to  any  object 
whatever,  even  though  one's  thoughts  be  not  actually 
directed  to  the  last  end.  Thus  while  walking  along  the 
road  one  needs  not  to  be  thinking  of  the  end  at  every  step. 

Seventh  Article, 
whether  all  men  have  the  same  last  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  all  men  have  not  the  same 
last  end.  For  before  all  else  the  unchangeable  good  seems 
to  be  the  last  end  of  man.  But  some  turn  away  from  the 
unchangeable  good,  by  sinning.  Therefore  all  men  have 
not  the  same  last  end. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  man's  entire  life  is  ruled  according  to 
his  last  end.  If,  therefore,  all  men  had  the  same  last  end, 
they  would  not  have  various  pursuits  in  life.  Which  is 
evidently  false. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  end  is  the  term  of  action.  But  actions 
are  of  individuals.  Now  although  men  agree  in  their  specific 
nature,  yet  they  differ  in  things  pertaining  to  individuals. 
Therefore  all  men  have  not  the  same  last  end. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Trin.  xiii.)  that  all 
men  agree  in  desiring  the  last  end,  which  is  happiness. 

/  answer  that,  We  can  speak  of  the  last  end  in  two  ways : 
first,  considering  only  the  aspect  of  last  end;  secondly, 
considering  the  thing  in  which  the  aspect  of  last  end  is 
realized.  So,  then,  as  to  the  aspect  of  last  end,  all  agree 
in  desiring  the  last  end:  since  all  desire  the  fulfilment  of 
their  perfection,  and  it  is  precisely  this  fulfilment  in  which 
the  last  end  consists,  as  stated  above  (A.  5).  But  as  to  the 
thing  in  which  this  aspect  is  realized,  all  men  are  not  agreed 
as  to  their  last  end:  since  some  desire  riches,  as  their  con- 


MAN'S  LAST  END  15 

summate  good;  some,  pleasure;  others,  something  else. 
Thus  to  every  taste  the  sweet  is  pleasant;  but  to  some, 
the  sweetness  of  wine  is  most  pleasant,  to  others,  the 
sweetness  of  honey,  or  of  something  similar.  Yet  that 
sweet  is  absolutely  the  best  of  all  pleasant  things,  in 
which  he  who  has  the  best  taste  takes  most  pleasure.  In 
like  manner  that  good  is  most  complete  which  the  man 
with  well-disposed  affections  desires  for  his  last  end. 

Rej)ly  Ohj.  i.  Those  who  sin  turn  from  that  in  which  their 
last  end  really  consists:  but  they  do  not  turn  away  from 
the  intention  of  the  last  end,  which  intention  they  mistakenly 
seek  in  other  things. 

Rej)ly  Ohj.  2.  Various  pursuits  in  life  are  found  among 
men  by  reason  of  the  various  things  in  which  men  seek  to 
find  their  last  end. 

Refly  Ohj.  3.  Although  actions  are  of  individuals,  yet 
their  first  principle  of  action  is  nature,  which  tends  to  one 
thing,  as  stated  above  (A.  5) . 

Eighth  Article, 
whether  other  creatures  concur  in  that  last  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  all  other  creatures  concur  in 
man's  last  end.  For  the  end  corresponds  to  the  beginning. 
But  man's  beginning — i.e.,  God — is  also  the  beginning  of  all 
else.     Therefore  all  other  things  concur  in  man's  last  end. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Dionysius  says  {Div.  Nom.  iv.)  that  God 
turns  all  things  to  Himself  as  to  their  last  end.  But  He  is 
also  man's  last  end;  because  He  alone  is  to  be  enjoyed  by 
man,  as  Augustine  says  (De  Doctr.  Christ,  i.).  Therefore 
other  things,  too,  concur  in  man's  last  end. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  man's  last  end  is  the  object  of  the  will. 
But  the  object  of  the  will  is  the  universal  good,  which  is 
the  end  of  all.  Therefore  all  must  needs  concur  in  man's 
last  end. 

On  the  contrary,  man's  last  end  is  happiness;  which  all 
men  desire,  as  Augustine  says  {De  Trin.  xiii.).     But  happi- 


i6  QUESTION  I 

ness  is  not  possible  for  animals  bereft  of  reason,  as  Augustine 
says  (Qq.  83).  Therefore  other  things  do  not  concur  in 
man's  last  end. 

/  answer  that,  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Phys.  ii.  and 
Metaph.  v.),  the  end  is  twofold, — the  end /or  which  and  the 
end  by  which  ;  viz.,  the  thing  itself  in  which  is  found  the 
aspect  of  good,  and  the  use  or  acquisition  of  that  thing. 
Thus  we  say  that  the  end  of  the  movement  of  a  weighty 
body  is  either  a  lower  place  as  thing,  or  to  be  in  a  lower 
place,  as  use  ;  and  the  end  of  the  miser  is  money  as  thing, 
or  possession  of  money  as  use. 

If,  therefore,  we  speak  of  man's  last  end  as  of  the  thing 
which  is  the  end,  thus  all  other  things  concur  in  man's  last 
end,  since  God  is  the  last  end  of  man  and  of  all  other  things. 
— If^  however,  we  speak  of  man's  last  end,  as  of  the  acquisi- 
tion of  the  end,  then  irrational  creatures  do  not  concur  with 
man  in  this  end.  For  man  and  other  rational  creatures 
attain  to  their  last  end  by  knowing  and  loving  God:  this 
is  not  possible  to  other  creatures,  which  acquire  their  last 
end,  in  so  far  as  they  share  in  the  Divine  likeness,  inasmuch 
as  they  are,  or  live,  or  even  know. 

Hence  it  is  evident  how  the  objections  are. solved:  since 
happiness  means  the  acquisition  of  the  last  end. 


.^"Wi»i35!y.g5-'^ 


QUESTION  II. 

OF  THOSE  THINGS  IN  WHICH  MAN^S  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS. 

[In  Eight  Articles.) 

We  have   now  to  consider  happiness:  and   (i)  in  what  it 
consists;  (2)  what  it  is;  (3)  how  we  can  obtain  it. 

Concerning  the  first  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  happiness  consists  in  wealth  ?  (2)  Whether  in 
honour  ?  (3)  Whether  in  fame  or  glory  ?  (4)  Whether  in 
power  ?  (5)  Whether  in  any  good  of  the  body  ?  (6)  Whether 
in  pleasure  ?  (7)  Whether  in  any  good  of  the  soul  ? 
(8)  Whether  in  any  created  good  ? 

First  Article. 

WHETHER   man's   HAPPINESS   CONSISTS   IN   WEALTH  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man's  happiness  consists  in 
wealth.  For  since  happiness  is  man's  last  end,  it  must 
consist  in  that  which  has  the  greatest  hold  on  man's  affec- 
tions. Now  this  is  wealth:  for  it  is  written  (Eccles.  x.  19) : 
All  things  obey  money.  Therefore  man's  happiness  consists 
in  wealth. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  according  to  Boethius  {De  Consol.  iii.), 
happiness  is  a  state  of  life  made  perfect  by  the  aggregate  of  all 
good  things.  Now  money  seems  to  be  the  means  of  possessing 
all  things:  for,  as  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  v.),  money  was 
invented,  that  it  might  be  a  sort  of  guarantee  for  the 
acquisition  of  whatever  man  desires.  Therefore  happiness 
consists  in  wealth. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  since  the  desire  for  the  sovereign  good 

II.  I  17  2 


i8  QUESTION  II 

never  fails,  it  seems  to  be  infinite.  But  this  is  the  case  with 
riches  more  tlian  anything  else;  since  a  covetous  man  shall 
not  be  satisfied  with  riches  (Eccles.  v.  9).  Therefore  happi- 
ness consists  in  wealth. 

On  the  contrary,  Man's  good  consists  in  retaining  happi- 
ness rather  than  in  spreading  it.  But  as  Boethius  says 
{De  Consol.  ii.),  wealth  shines  in  giving  rather  than  in  hoarding  : 
for  the  miser  is  hateful,  whereas  the  generous  man  is  ap- 
plauded. Therefore  man's  happiness  does  not  consist  in 
wealth. 

/  answer  that,  It  is  impossible  for  man's  happiness  to  con- 
sist in  wealth.  For  wealth  is  twofold,  as  the  Philosopher 
says  {Polit.  i.),  viz.,  natural  and  artificial.  Natural  wealth 
is  that  which  serves  man  as  a  remedy  for  his  natural  wants : 
such  as  food,  drink,  clothing,  cars,  dwellings,  and  such- 
like, while  artificial  wealth  is  that  which  is  not  a  direct 
help  to  nature,  as  money;  but  this  is  invented  by  the  art  of 
man,  for  the  convenience  of  exchange,  and  as  a  measure  of 
things  saleable. 

Now  it  is  evident  that  man's  happiness  cannot  consist  in 
natural  wealth.  For  wealth  of  this  kind  is  sought  for  the 
sake  of  something  else,  viz.,  as  a  support  of  human  nature: 
consequently  it  cannot  be  man's  last  end,  rather  is  it 
ordained  to  man  as  to  its  end.  Wherefore  in  the  order  of 
nature,  all  such  things  are  below  man,  and  made  for  him, 
according  to  Ps.  viii.  8 :  Thou  hast  subjected  all  things  under 
his  feet. 

And  as  to  artificial  wealth,  it  is  not  sought  save  for  the 
sake  of  natural  wealth;  since  man  would  not  seek  it  except 
because,  by  its  means,  he  procures  for  himself  the  necessaries 
of  life.  Consequently  much  less  can  it  be  considered  in  the 
light  of  the  last  end.  Therefore  it  is  impossible  for  happi- 
ness, which  is  the  last  end  of  man,  to  consist  in  wealth. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  All  material  things  obey  money,  so  far  as 
the  multitude  of  fools  is  concerned,  who  know  no  other 
than  material  goods,  which  can  be  obtained  for  money. 
But  we  should  take  our  estimation  of  human  goods  not 
from  the  foolish  but  from  the  wise:  just  as  it  is  for  a  person, 


IN  WHAT  MAN'S  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS         19 

whose  sense  of  taste  is  in  good  order,  to  judge  whether  a 
thing  is  palatable. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  All  things  saleable  can  be  had  for  money: 
not  so  spiritual  things,  which  cannot  be  sold.  Hence  it  is 
written  (Prov.  xvii.  16) :  What  doth  it  avail  a  fool  to  have 
riches,  seeing  he  cannot  buy  wisdom  ? 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  desire  for  natural  riches  is  not  infinite: 
because  they  suffice  for  nature  in  a  certain  measure.  But 
the  desire  for  artificial  wealth  is  infinite,  for  it  is  the  servant 
of  disordered  concupiscence,  which  is  not  curbed,  as  the 
Philosopher  makes  clear  {Polit.  i.).  Yet  this  desire  for 
wealth  is  infinite  otherwise  than  the  desire  for  the  sovereign 
good.  For  the  more  perfectly  the  sovereign  good  is  pos- 
sessed, the  more  is  it  loved,  and  other  things  despised: 
because  the  more  we  possess  it,  the  more  we  know  it. 
Hence  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  xxiv.  29) :  They  that  eat  me 
shall  yet  hunger.  Whereas  in  the  desire  for  wealth  and  for 
whatsoever  temporal  goods,  the  contrary  is  the  case:  for 
when  we  already  possess  them,  we  despise  them,  and  seek 
others :  which  is  the  sense  of  Our  Lord's  words  (John  iv.  13) : 
Whosoever  drinketh  of  this  water,  by  which  temporal  goods 
are  signified,  shall  thirst  again.  The  reason  of  this  is  that 
we  realize  more  their  insufficiency  when  we  possess  them: 
and  this  very  fact  shows  that  they  are  imperfect,  and  that 
the  sovereign  good  does  not  consist  therein. 

Second  Article. 

WHETHER  man's    HAPPINESS    CONSISTS   IN   HONOURS  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  man's  happiness  consists  in 
honours.  For  happiness  or  bliss  is  the  reward  of  virtue,  as 
the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  i.).  But  honour  more  than 
anything  else  seems  to  be  that  by  which  virtue  is  rewarded, 
as  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.).  Therefore  happiness 
consists  especiaUy  in  honours. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  that  which  belongs  to  God  and  to  persons 
of  great  excellence  seems  especially  to  be  happiness,  which 


20  QUESTION  II 

is  the  perfect  good.  But  that  is  honour,  as  the  Philosopher 
says  [Ethic,  iv.).  Moreover,  the  Apostle  says  (i  Tim.  i.  17) : 
To  .  .  .  the  only  God  he  honour  and  glory.  Therefore  happi- 
ness consists  in  honour. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  that  which  man  desires  above  all  is 
happiness.  But  nothing  seems  more  desirable  to  man  than 
honour:  since  man  suffers  loss  in  all  other  things,  lest  he 
should  suffer  loss  of  honour.  Therefore  happiness  consists 
in  honour. 

On  the  contrary,  Happiness  is  in  the  happy.  But  honour 
is  not  in  the  honoured,  but  rather  in  him  who  honours,  and 
who  offers  deference  to  the  person  honoured,  as  the  Philos- 
opher says  {Ethic  i.).  Therefore  happiness  does  not  con- 
sist in  honour. 

/  answer  that,  It  is  impossible  for  happiness  to  consist 
in  honour.  For  honour  is  given  to  a  man  on  account  of 
some  excellence  in  him;  and  consequently  it  is  a  sign  and 
attestation  of  the  excellence  that  is  in  the  person  honoured. 
Now  a  man's  excellence  is  in  proportion,  especially,  to  his 
happiness,  which  is  man's  perfect  good;  and  to  its  parts,  i.e., 
those  goods  by  which  he  has  a  certain  share  of  happiness. 
And  therefore  honour  can  result  from  happiness,  but  happi- 
ness cannot  principally  consist  therein. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  the  Philosopher  says  {ihid.),  honour  is  not 
that  reward  of  virtue,  for  which  the  virtuous  work :  but  they 
receive  honour  from  men  by  way  of  reward,  as  from  those 
who  have  nothing  greater  to  offer.  But  virtue's  true  reward 
is  happiness  itself,  for  which  the  virtuous  work:  whereas  if 
they  worked  for  honour,  it  would  no  longer  be  virtue,  but 
ambition. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Honour  is  due  to  God  and  to  persons  of 
great  exceUence  as  a  sign  or  attestation  of  excellence  already 
existing:  not  that  honour  makes  them  excellent. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  That  man  desires  honour  above  all  else, 
arises  from  his  natural  desire  for  happiness,  from  which 
honour  results,  as  stated  above.  Wherefore  man  seeks  to 
be  honoured  especially  by  the  wise,  on  whose  judgment  he 
believes  himself  to  be  excellent  or  happy. 


IN  WHAT  MAN'S  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS         21 
Third  Article. 

WHETHER  man's   HAPPINESS   CONSISTS  IN   FAME  OR  GLORY  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man's  happiness  consists  in 
glory.  For  happiness  seems  to  consist  in  that  which  is 
paid  to  the  saints  for  the  trials  they  have  undergone  in  the 
world.  But  this  is  glory:  for  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  viii.  18) 
The  sufferings  of  this  time  are  not  worthy  to  he  compared  with 
the  glory  to  come,  that  shall  he  revealed  in  us.  Therefore 
happiness  consists  in  glory. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  good  is  diffusive,  as  stated  by  Dionysius 
{Div.  Nom.  iv.).  But  man's  good  is  spread  abroad  in  the 
knowledge  of  others  by  glory  more  than  by  anything  else: 
since,  according  to  Ambrose  (Augustine, — Contra  Maxim. 
Arian.  ii.),  glory  consists  in  heing  well  known  and  praised. 
Therefore  man's  happiness  consists  in  glory. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  happiness  is  the  most  enduring  good. 
Now  this  seems  to  be  fame  or  glory:  because  by  this  men 
attain  to  eternity  after  a  fashion.  Hence  Boethius  says 
[De  Consol.  iii.) :  You  seem  to  beget  unto  yourselves  eternity, 
when  you  think  of  your  fame  in  future  time.  .  Therefore  man's 
happiness  consists  in  fame  or  glory. 

On  the  contrary.  Happiness  is  man's  true  good.  But  it 
happens  that  fame  or  glory  is  false:  for  as  Boethius  says 
{De  Consol.  iii.),  many  owe  their  renown  to  the  lying  reports 
spread  among  the  people.  Can  anything  he  more  shamefid? 
For  those  who  receive  false  fame,  must  needs  blush  at  their 
own  praise.  Therefore  man's  happiness  does  not  consist 
in  fame  or  glory. 

/  answer  that,  Man's  happiness  cannot  consist  in  human 
fame  or  glory.  For  glory  consists  in  heing  well  known  and 
praised,  as  Ambrose  (Augustine,  loc.  cit.)  says.  Now  the 
thing  known  is  related  to  human  knowledge  otherwise  than 
to  God's  knowledge :  for  human  knowledge  is  caused  by  the 
things  known,  whereas  God's  knowledge  is  the  cause  of  the 
things  known.     Wherefore  the  perfection  of  human  good. 


22  QUESTION  II 

which  is  called  happiness,  cannot  be  caused  by  human 
knowledge :  but  rather  human  knowledge  of  another's  happi- 
ness proceeds  from,  and,  in  a  fashion,  is  caused  by,  human 
happiness  itself,  inchoate  or  perfect.  Consequently  man's 
happiness  cannot  consist  in  fame  or  glory.  On  the  other 
hand,  man's  good  depends  on  God's  knowledge  as  its  cause. 
And  therefore  man's  beatitude  depends,  as  on  its  cause,  on 
the  glory  which  man  has  with  God;  according  to  Ps.  xc. 
15,  16:  /  will  deliver  him,  and  I  will  glorify  him  ;  I  will  fill 
him  with  length  of  days,  and  I  will  show  him  my  salvation. 

Furthermore,  we  must  observe  that  human  knowledgs 
often  fails,  especially  in  contingent  singulars,  such  as  are 
human  acts.  For  this  reason  human  glory  is  frequently 
deceptive.  But  since  God  cannot  be  deceived,  His  glory 
is  always  true;  hence  it  is  written  (2  Cor.  x.  18):  He  is 
approved,  whom  God  commends. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  Apostle  speaks,  then,  not  of  the  glory 
which  is  with  men,  but  of  the  glory  which  is  from  God,  with 
His  angels.  Hence  it  is  written  (Mark  viii.) :  The  Son  of 
Man  shall  confess  him  in  the  glory  of  His  Father,  before  His 
angels.^ 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  man's  good  which,  through  fame  or  glory, 
is  in  the  knowledge  of  many,  if  this  knowledge  be  true, 
must  needs  be  derived  from  good  existing  in  the  man  him- 
self: and  hence  it  presupposes  perfect  or  inchoate  happiness. 
But  if  the  knowledge  be  false,  it  does  not  harmonize  with 
the  thing:  and  thus  good  does  not  exist  in  him  who  is 
looked  upon  as  famous.  Hence  it  follows  that  fame  can 
nowise  make  man  happy. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Fame  has  no  stability;  in  fact,  it  is  easily 
ruined  by  false  report.  And  if  sometimes  it  endures,  this  is 
by  accident.     But  happiness  endures  of  itself,  and  for  ever. 

*  St.  Thomas  joins  Mark  viii,  38  with  Luke  xii.  8,  owing  to  a 
possible  variant  in  his  text,  or  to  the  fact  that  he  was  quoting 
from  memory. 


IN  WHAT  MAN'S  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS         23 
Fourth  Article. 

WHETHER   man's    HAPPINESS    CONSISTS   IN    POWER  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  happiness  consists  in  power. 
For  all  things  desire  to  become  like  to  God,  as  to  their 
last  end  and  first  beginning.  But  men  who  are  in  power, 
seem,  on  account  of  the  similarity  of  power,  to  be  most  like 
to  God:  hence  also  in  Scripture  they  are  called  gods  (Exod. 
xxii.  8), — Thou  shalt  not  speak  ill  of  the  gods.  Therefore 
happiness  consists  in  power. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  happiness  is  the  perfect  good.  But  the 
highest  perfection  for  man  is  to  be  able  to  rule  others ;  which 
belongs  to  those  who  are  in  power.  Therefore  happiness 
consists  in  power. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  since  happiness  is  supremely  desirable, 
it  is  contrary  to  that  which  is  before  all  to  be  shunned. 
But,  more  than  aught  else,  men  shun  servitude,  which  is 
contrary  to  power.     Therefore  happiness  consists  in  power. 

On  the  contrary,  Happiness  is  the  perfect  good.  But 
power  is  most  imperfect.  For  as  Boethius  says  {De  Con- 
sol,  iii.),  the  power  of  man  cannot  relieve  the  gnawings  of 
care,  nor  can  it  avoid  the  thorny  path  of  anxiety:  and  further 
on:  Think  you  a  man  is  powerful  who  is  surrounded  by 
attendants,  whom  he  inspires  with  fear  indeed,  but  whom  he 
fears  still  more  ?  Therefore  happiness  does  not  consist  in 
power. 

/  answer  that.  It  is  impossible  for  happiness  to  consist  in 
power;  and  this  for  two  reasons.  First  because  power  has 
the  nature  of  principle,  as  is  stated  in  Metaph.  v.,  whereas 
happiness  has  the  nature  of  last  end. — Secondly,  because 
power  has  relation  to  good  and  evil:  whereas  happiness  is 
man's  proper  and  perfect  good.  Wherefore  some  happiness 
might  consist  in  the  good  use  of  power,  which  is  by  virtue, 
rather  than  in  power  itself. 

Now  four  general  reasons  may  be  given  to  prove  that 
happiness  consists  in  none  of  the  foregoing  external  goods. 


24  QUESTION  II 

First,  because,  since  happiness  is  man's  supreme  good,  it  is 
incompatible  with  any  evil.  Now  all  the  foregoing  can  be 
found  both  in  good  and  in  evil  men. — Secondly,  because, 
since  it  is  the  nature  of  happiness  to  satisfy  of  itself,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  i.,  having  gained  happiness,  man  cannot 
lack  any  needful  good.  But  after  acquiring  any  one  of  the 
foregoing,  man  may  still  lack  many  goods  that  are  necessary 
to  him;  for  instance,  wisdom,  bodily  health,  and  suchlike. — 
Thirdly,  because,  since  happiness  is  the  perfect  good,  no 
evil  can  accrue  to  anyone  therefrom.  This  cannot  be 
said  of  the  foregoing:  for  it  is  written  (Eccles.  v.  12)  that 
riches  are  sometimes  kej)t  to  the  hurt  of,  the  owner  :  and  the 
same  may  be  said  of  the  other  three. — Fourthly,  because 
man  is  ordained  to  happiness  through  principles  that  are  in 
him;  since  he  is  ordained  thereto  naturally.  Now  the  four 
goods  mentioned  above  are  due  rather  to  external  causes, 
and  in  most  cases  to  fortune;  for  which  reason  they  are 
called  goods  of  fortune.  Therefore  it  is  evident  that  happi- 
ness nowise  consists  in  the  foregoing. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  God's  power  is  His  goodness  :  hence  He 
cannot  use  His  power  otherwise  than  well.  But  it  is  not 
so  with  men.  Consequently  it  is  not  enough  for  man's 
happiness,  that  he  become  like  God  in  power,  unless  he 
become  like  Him  in  goodness  also. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Just  as  it  is  a  very  good  thing  for  a  man 
to  make  good  use  of  power  in  ruling  many,  so  is  it  a  very 
bad  thing  if  he  makes  a  bad  use  of  it.  And  so  it  is  that 
power  is  towards  good  and  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Servitude  is  a  hindrance  to  the  good  use  of 
power:  therefore  is  it  that  men  naturally  shun  it;  not 
because  man's  supreme  good  consists  in  power. 

Fifth  Article. 

WHETHER  man's  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS  IN  ANY  BODILY  GOOD  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 
Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  man's  happiness  consists  in 
bodily  goods.     For  it  is  written  (Ecclus.  xxx.  16) :  There  is 


IN  WHAT  MAN'S  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS         25 

no  riches  above  the  riches  of  the  health  of  the  body.  But 
happiness  consists  in  that  which  is  best.  Therefore  it 
consists  in  the  health  of  the  body. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Dionysius  says  [Div.  Nom.  v.),  that  to 
be  is  better  than  to  live,  and  to  live  is  better  than  all  that 
follows.  But  for  man's  being  and  living,  the  health  of  the 
body  is  necessary.  Since,  therefore,  happiness  is  man's 
supreme  good,  it  seems  that  health  of  the  body  belongs 
more  than  anything  else  to  happiness. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  more  universal  a  thing  is,  the  higher 
the  principle  from  which  it  depends;  because  the  higher  a 
cause  is,  the  greater  the  scope  of  its  power.  Now  just  as 
the  causality  of  the  efficient  cause  consists  in  its  flowing 
into  something,  so  the  causality  of  the  end  consists  in  its 
drawing  the  appetite.  Therefore,  just  as  the  First  Cause 
is  that  which  flows  into  all  things,  so  the  last  end  is  that 
which  attracts  the  desire  of  all.  But  being  itself  is  that 
which  is  most  desired  by  all.  Therefore  man's  happiness 
consists  most  of  all  in  things  pertaining  to  his  being,  such 
as  the  health  of  the  body. 

On  the  contrary,  Man  surpasses  all  other  animals  in  regard 
to  happiness.  But  in  bodily  goods  he  is  surpassed  by  many 
animals:  for  instance,  by  the  elephant  in  longevity;  by 
the  lion  in  strength;  by  the  stag  in  fleetness.  Therefore 
man's  happiness  does  not  consist  in  goods  of  the  body. 

/  answer  that,  It  is  impossible  for  man's  happiness  to 
consist  in  the  goods  of  the  body;  and  this  for  two  reasons. 
First,  because,  if  a  thing  be  ordained  to  another  as  to  its 
end,  its  last  end  cannot  consist  in  the  preservation  of  its 
being.  Hence  a  captain  does  not  intend,  as  a  last  end, 
the  preservation  of  the  ship  entrusted  to  him,  since  a  ship 
is  ordained  to  something  else  as  an  end,  viz.,  to  navigation. 
Now  just  as  the  ship  is  entrusted  to  the  captain  that  he  may 
steer  its  course,  so  man  is  given  over  to  his  will  and  reason; 
according  to  Ecclus.  xv.  14 :  God  made  man  from  the  begin- 
ning and  left  him  in  the  hand  of  his  own  counsel.  Now  it  is 
evident  that  man  is  ordained  to  something  as  his  end:  since 
man  is  not  the  supreme  good.     Therefore  the  last  end  of 


26  QUESTION  II 

man's  reason  and  will  cannot  be  the  preservation  of  man's 
being. 

Secondly,  because,  granted  that  the  end  of  man's  will 
and  reason  be  the  preservation  of  man's  being,  it  could 
not  be  said  that  the  end  of  man  is  some  good  of  the  body. 
For  man's  being  consists  in  soul  and  body;  and  though  the 
being  of  the  body  depends  on  the  soul,  yet  the  being  of  the 
human  soul  depends  not  on  the  body,  as  shown  above 
(I.,  Q.  LXXV.,  A.  2) ;  and  the  very  body  is  for  the  soul,  as 
matter  for  its  form,  and  the  instruments  for  the  man  that 
puts  them  into  motion,  that  by  their  means  he  may  do  his 
work.  Wherefore  all  goods  of  the  body  are  ordained  to 
the  goods  of  the  soul,  as  to  their  end.  Consequently  happi- 
ness, which  is  man's  last  end,  cannot  consist  in  goods  of  the 
body. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Just  as  the  body  is  ordained  to  the  soul, 
as  its  end,  so  are  external  goods  ordained  to  the  body  itself. 
And  therefore  it  is  with  reason  that  the  good  of  the  body 
is  preferred  to  external  goods,  which  are  signified  by  riches, 
just  as  the  good  of  the  soul  is  preferred  to  all  bodily  goods. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Being  taken  simply,  as  including  all  per- 
fection of  being,  surpasses  life  and  all  that  follows  it;  for 
thus  being  itself  includes  all  these.  And  in  this  sense 
Dionysius  speaks.  But  if  we  consider  being  itself  as 
participated  in  this  or  that  thing,  which  does  not  possess 
the  whole  perfection  of  being,  but  has  imperfect  being, 
such  as  the  being  of  any  creature;  then  it  is  evident  that 
being  itself  together  with  an  additional  perfection  is  more 
excellent.  Hence  in  the  same  passage  Dionysius  says  that 
things  that  live  are  better  than  things  that  exist,  and  intelli- 
gent better  than  living  things. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Since  the  end  corresponds  to  the  beginning, 
this  argument  proves  that  the  last  end  is  the  first  begin- 
ning of  being,  in  Whom  every  perfection  of  being  is :  Whose 
likeness,  according  to  their  proportion,  some  desire  as  to 
being  only,  some  as  to  living  being,  some  as  to  being  which 
is  living,  intelligent  and  happy.     And  this  belongs  to  few. 


IN  WHAT  MAN'S  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS        27 
Sixth  Article. 

WHETHER  man's   HAPPINESS   CONSISTS   IN   PLEASURE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man's  happiness  consists  in 
pleasure.  For  since  happiness  is  the  last  end,  it  is  not 
desired  for  something  else,  but  other  things  for  it.  But 
this  answers  to  pleasure  more  than  to  anything  else :  for  it 
is  absurd  to  ask  anyone  what  is  his  motive  in  wishing  to  be 
pleased  {Ethic,  x.).  Therefore  happiness  consists  princi- 
pally in  pleasure  and  delight. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  first  cause  goes  more  deeply  into  the 
effect  than  the  second  cause  (De  Causis  i.).  Now  the  causality 
of  the  end  consists  in  its  attracting  the  appetite.  There- 
fore, seemingly  that  which  moves  most  the  appetite, 
answers  to  the  notion  of  the  last  end.  Now  this  is  pleasure : 
and  a  sign  of  this  is  that  delight  so  far  absorbs  man's  will 
and  reason,  that  it  causes  him  to  despise  other  goods, 
Therefore  it  seems  that  man's  last  end,  which  is  happiness, 
consists  principally  in  pleasure. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  since  desire  is  for  good,  it  seems  that 
what  all  desire  is  best.  But  all  desire  deHght;  both  wise 
and  foolish,  and  even  irrational  creatures.  Therefore 
deHght  is  the  best  of  all.  Therefore  happiness,  which  is 
the  supreme  good,  consists  in  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  Boethius  says  (De  Consol.  iii.) :  Any  one 
that  chooses  to  look  back  on  his  past  excesses,  will  perceive  that 
pleasures  have  a  sad  ending  :  and  if  they  can  render  a  man 
happy,  there  is  no  reason  why  we  should  not  say  that  the 
very  beasts  are  happy  too. 

I  answer  that,  Because  bodily  dehghts  are  more  generally 
known,  the  name  of  pleasure  has  been  appropriated  to  them 
{Ethic,  vii.),  although  other  dehghts  excel  them:  and  yet 
happiness  does  not  consist  in  them.  Because  in  every 
thing,  that  which  pertains  to  its  essence  is  distinct  from 
its  proper  accident:  thus  in  man  it  is  one  thing  that  he  is  a 
mortal  rational   animal,  and   another   that   he   is  a  risible 


28  QUESTION  II 

animal.  We  must  therefore  consider  that  every  deHght  is 
a  proper  accident  resulting  from  happiness,  or  from  some 
part  of  happiness;  since  the  reason  that  a  man  is  delighted 
is  that  he  has  some  fitting  good,  either  in  reality,  or  in 
hope,  or  at  least  in  memory.  Now  a  fitting  good,  if  indeed 
it  be  the  perfect  good,  is  precisely  man's  happiness:  and  if 
it  is  imperfect,  it  is  a  share  of  happiness,  either  proximate, 
or  remote,  or  at  least  apparent.  Therefore  it  is  evident 
that  neither  is  delight,  which  results  from  the  perfect  good, 
the  very  essence  of  happiness,  but  something  resulting 
therefrom  as  its  proper  accident. 

But  bodily  pleasure  cannot  result  from  the  perfect  good 
even  in  that  way.  For  it  results  from  a  good  apprehended 
by  sense,  which  is  a  power  of  the  soul,  which  power  makes 
use  of  the  body.  Now  good  pertaining  to  the  body,  and 
apprehended  by  sense,  cannot  be  man's  perfect  good.  For 
since  the  rational  soul  excels  the  capacity  of  corporeal  matter, 
that  part  of  the  soul  which  is  independent  of  a  corporeal 
organ,  has  a  certain  infinity  in  regard  to  the  body  and  those 
parts  of  the  soul  which  are  tied  down  to  the  body:  just  as 
immaterial  things  are  in  a  way  infinite  as  compared  to 
material  things,  since  a  form  is,  after  a  fashion,  contracted 
and  bounded  by  matter,  so  that  a  form  which  is  independent 
of  matter  is,  in  a  way,  infinite.  Therefore  sense,  which  is 
a  power  of  the  body,  knows  the  singular,  which  is  deter- 
minate through  matter:  whereas  the  intellect,  which  is  a 
power  independent  of  matter,  knows  the  universal,  which  is 
abstracted  from  matter,  and  contains  an  infinite  number  of 
singulars.  Consequently  it  is  evident  that  good  which  is 
fitting  to  the  body,  and  which  causes  bodily  delight  through 
being  apprehended  by  sense,  is  not  man's  perfect  good,  but 
is  quite  a  trifle  as  compared  with  the  good  of  the  soul. 
Hence  it  is  written  (Wisd.  vii.  9)  that  all  gold  in  comparison 
of  her,  is  as  a  little  sand.  And  therefore  bodily  pleasure  is 
neither  happiness  itself,  nor  a  proper  accident  of  happiness. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  It  comes  to  the  same  whether  we  desire 
good,  or  desire  delight,  which  is  nothing  else  than  the 
appetite's  rest  in  good :  thus  it  is  owing  to  the  same  natural 


IN  WHAT  MAN'S  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS         29 

force  that  a  weighty  body  is  borne  downwards  and  that  it 
rests  there.  Consequently  just  as  good  is  desired  for  itself, 
so  delight  is  desired  for  itself  and  not  for  anything  else,  if 
the  preposition  for  denote  the  final  cause.  But  if  it  denote 
the  formal  or  rather  the  motive  cause,  thus  delight  is 
desirable  for  something  else,  i.e.,  for  the  good,  which  is  the 
object  of  that  delight,  and  consequently  is  its  principle,  and 
gives  it  its  form:  for  the  reason  that  delight  is  desired  is 
that  it  is  rest  in  the  thing  desired. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  vehemence  of  desire  for  sensible  delight 
arises  from  the  fact  that  operations  of  the  senses,  through 
being  the  principles  of  our  knowledge,  are  more  perceptible. 
And  so  it  is  that  sensible  pleasures  are  desired  by  the 
majority. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  All  desire  delight  in  the  same  way  as  they 
desire  good:  and  yet  they  desire  delight  by  reason  of  the 
good  and  not  conversely,  as  stated  above  [ad  i).  Conse- 
quently it  does  not  follow  that  delight  is  the  supreme  and 
essential  good,  but  that  every  delight  results  from  some 
good,  and  that  some  delight  results  from  that  which  is  the 
essential  and  supreme  good. 

Seventh  Article. 

WHETHER   SOME    GOOD    OF   THE   SOUL   CONSTITUTES   MAN's 

HAPPINESS  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  some  good  of  the  soul  constitutes 
man's  happiness.  For  happiness  is  man's  good.  Now  this 
is  threefold,  external  goods,  goods  of  the  body,  and  goods 
of  the  soul.  But  happiness  does  not  consist  in  external 
goods,  nor  in  goods  of  the  body,  as  shown  above  (AA.  4,  5). 
Therefore  it  consists  in  goods  of  the  soul. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  we  love  that  for  which  we  desire  good, 
more  than  the  good  that  we  desire  for  it:  thus  we  love  a 
friend  for  whom  we  desire  money,  more  than  we  love  money. 
But  whatever  good  a  man  desires,  he  desires  it  for  himself. 
Therefore  he  loves  himself  more  than  all  other  goods.    Now 


30  QUESTION  II 

happiness  is  what  is  loved  above  all:  which  is  evident  from 
the  fact  that  for  its  sake  all  else  is  loved  and  desired. 
Therefore  happiness  consists  in  some  good  of  man  himself: 
not,  however,  in  goods  of  the  body;  therefore,  in  goods  of 
the  soul. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  perfection  is  something  belonging  to  that 
which  is  perfected.  But  happiness  is  a  perfection  of  man. 
Therefore  happiness  is  something  belonging  to  man.  But 
it  is  not  something  belonging  to  the  body,  as  shown  above 
(A.  5).  Therefore  it  is  something  belonging  to  the  soul;  and 
thus  it  consists  in  goods  of  the  soul. 

On  the  contrary,  As  Augustine  says  {De  Doctr.  Christ,  i.), 
that  which  constitutes  the  life  of  happiness  is  to  he  loved  for 
its  own  sake.  But  man  is  not  to  be  loved  for  his  own  sake, 
but  whatever  is  in  man  is  to  be  loved  for  God's  sake.  There- 
fore happiness  consists  in  no  good  of  the  soul. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  i,  A.  2),  the  end  is 
twofold :  namely,  the  thing  itself,  which  we  desire  to  attain ; 
and  the  use,  namely,  the  attainment  or  possession  of  that 
thing.  If,  then,  we  speak  of  man's  last  end,  as  to  the  thing 
itself  which  we  desire  as  last  end,  it  is  impossible  for  man's 
last  end  to  be  the  soul  itself  or  something  belonging  to  it. 
Because  the  soul,  considered  in  itself,  is  as  something  exist- 
ing in  potentiality:  for  it  becomes  knowing  actually,  from 
being  potentially  knowing;  and  actually  virtuous,  from 
being  potentially  virtuous.  Now  since  potentiality  is  for 
the  sake  of  act,  that  which  in  itself  is  in  potentiality  cannot 
be  the  last  end.  Therefore  the  soul  itself  cannot  be  its 
own  last  end. 

In  like  manner  neither  can  anything  belonging  to  it, 
whether  power,  habit,  or  act.  For  that  good  which  is  the 
last  end,  is  the  perfect  good  fulfilling  the  desire.  Now 
man's  appetite,  otherwise  the  will,  is  for  the  universal  good. 
And  any  good  inherent  to  the  soul  is  a  participated  good, 
and  consequently  a  portioned  good.  Therefore  none  of 
them  can  be  man's  last  end. 

But  if  we  speak  of  man's  last  end,  as  to  the  attainment 
or  possession  thereof,  or  as  to  any  use  whatever  of  the 


IN  WHAT  MAN'S  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS        31 

thing  itself  desired  as  an  end,  thus  does  something  of  man, 
in  respect  of  his  soul,  belong  to  his  last  end :  since  man  attains 
happiness  through  his  soul.  Therefore  the  thing  itself  which 
is  desired  as  end,  is  that  which  constitutes  happiness,  and 
makes  man  happy;  but  the  attainment  of  this  thing  is 
called  happiness.  Consequently  we  must  say  that  happi- 
ness is  something  belonging  to  the  soul;  but  that  which 
constitutes  happiness  is  something  outside  the  soul. 

Refly  Ohj.  i.  Inasmuch  as  this  division  includes  all  goods 
that  man  can  desire,  thus  the  good  of  the  soul  is  not  only 
power,  habit,  or  act,  but  also  the  object  of  these,  which  is 
something  outside.  And  in  this  way  nothing  hinders  us 
from  saying  that  what  constitutes  happiness  is  a  good  of 
the  soul. 

Re  fly  Ohj.  2.  As  far  as  the  proposed  objection  is  con- 
cerned, happiness  is  loved  above  all,  as  the  good  desired; 
whereas  a  friend  is  loved  as  that  to  which  good  is  desired; 
and  thus,  too,  man  loves  himself.  Consequently  it  is  not 
the  same  kind  of  love  in  both  cases.  As  to  whether  man 
loves  anything  more  than  himself  with  the  love  of  friendship, 
there  will  be  occasion  to  inquire  when  we  treat  of  Charity. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Happiness  itself,  since  it  is  a  perfection  of 
the  soul,  is  an  inherent  good  of  the  soul;  but  that  which 
constitutes  happiness,  viz.,  which  makes  man  happy,  is 
something  outside  his  soul,  as  stated  above. 

Eighth  Article. 

WHETHER   ANY    CREATED    GOOD    CONSTITUTES   MAN's 

HAPPINESS  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  some  created  good  constitutes 
man's  happiness.  For  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Norn,  vii.)  that 
Divine  wisdom  unites  the  ends  of  first  things  to  the  beginnings 
of  second  things,  from  which  we  may  gather  that  the  summit 
of  a  lower  nature  touches  the  base  of  the  higher  nature.  But 
man's  highest  good  is  happiness.  Since  then  the  angel 
is  above  man  in  the  order  of  nature,  as  stated  in  the  First 


32  QUESTION  II 

Part  (Q.  CXL,  A.  i),  it  seems  that  man's  happiness  consists 
in  man  somehow  reaching  the  angel. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  last  end  of  each  thing  is  that  which, 
in  relation  to  it,  is  perfect :  hence  the  part  is  for  the  whole, 
as  for  its  end.  But  the  universe  of  creatures  which  is  called 
the  macrocosm,  is  compared  to  man  who  is  called  the 
microcosm  [Phys.  viii.),  as  perfect  to  imperfect.  Therefore 
man's  happiness  consists  in  the  whole  universe  of  creatures. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  man  is  made  happy  by  that  which  lulls 
his  natural  desire.  But  man's  natural  desire  does  not  reach 
out  to  a  good  surpassing  his  capacity.  Since  then  man's 
capacity  does  not  include  that  good  which  surpasses  the 
limits  of  all  creation,  it  seems  that  man  can  be  made  happy 
by  some  created  good.  Consequently  some  created  good 
constitutes  man's  happiness. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Civ.  Dei.  xix.) :  As 
the  soul  is  the  life  of  the  body,  so  God  is  man's  life  of  happi- 
ness :  of  Whom  it  is  written  :  '  Happy  is  that  people  whose 
God  is  the  Lord  '  (Ps.  cxliii.  15). 

/  answer  that,  It  is  impossible  for  any  created  good  to  con- 
stitute man's  happiness.  For  happiness  is  the  perfect  good, 
which  lulls  the  appetite  altogether ;  else  it  would  not  be  the 
last  end,  if  something  yet  remained  to  be  desired.  Now 
the  object  of  the  will,  i.e.,  of  man's  appetite,  is  the  universal 
good;  just  as  the  object  of  the  intellect,  is  the  universal 
true.  Hence  it  is  evident  that  naught  can  lull  man's  will, 
save  the  universal  good.  This  is  to  be  found,  not  in  any 
creature,  but  in  God  alone;  because  every  creature  has 
goodness  by  participation.  Wherefore  God  alone  can  satisfy 
the  will  of  man,  according  to  the  words  of  Ps.  cii.  5:  Who 
satisfieth  thy  desire  with  good  things.  Therefore  God  alone 
constitutes  man's  happiness. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  summit  of  man  does  indeed  touch  the 
base  of  the  angelic  nature,  by  a  kind  of  likeness;  but  man 
does  not  rest  there  as  in  his  last  end,  but  reaches  out  to  the 
universal  fount  itself  of  good,  which  is  the  common  object 
of  happiness  of  all  the  blessed,  as  being  the  infinite  and 
perfect  good. 


IN  WHAT  MAN'S  HAPPINESS  CONSISTS        33 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  If  a  whole  be  not  the  last  end,  but  ordained 
to  a  further  end,  then  the  last  end  of  a  part  thereof,  is  not 
the  whole  itself,  but  something  else.  Now  the  universe  of 
creatures,  to  which  man  is  compared  as  part  to  whole,  is 
not  the  last  end,  but  is  ordained  to  God,  as  to  its  last  end. 
Therefore  the  last  end  of  man  is  not  the  good  of  the  universe, 
but  God  Himself. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Created  good  is  not  less  than  that  good  of 
which  man  is  capable,  as  of  something  intrinsic  and  in- 
herent to  him:  but  it  is  less  than  the  good  of  which  he  is 
capable,  as  of  an  object,  and  which  is  infinite.  And  the 
participated  good  which  is  in  an  angel,  and  in  the  whole 
universe,  is  a  finite  and  restricted  good. 


II.  I 


QUESTION  III. 

WHAT  IS  HAPPINESS. 

{In  Eight  Articles.) 

We  have  now  to  consider  (i)  what  happiness  is,  and  (2)  what 
things  are  required  for  it. 

Concerning  the  first  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  happiness  is  something  uncreated  ?  (2)  If 
it  be  something  created,  whether  it  is  an  operation  ? 
(3)  Whether  it  is  an  operation  of  the  sensitive,  or  only  of 
the  intellectual  part  ?  (4)  If  it  be  an  operation  of  the 
intellectual  part,  whether  it  is  an  operation  of  the  intellect, 
or  of  the  will  ?  (5)  If  it  be  an  operation  of  the  intellect, 
whether  it  is  an  operation  of  the  speculative  or  of  the 
practical  intellect  ?  (6)  If  it  be  an  operation  of  the  specula- 
tive intellect,  whether  it  consist  in  the  considerations  of 
speculative  sciences  ?  (7)  Whether  it  consists  in  the  con- 
sideration of  separate  substances,  viz.,  angels  ?  (8)  Whether 
it  consists  in  the  sole  contemplation  of  God  seen  in  His 
Essence  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  happiness  is  something  uncreated  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article: — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  happiness  is  something  un- 
created. For  Boethius  says  [De  Consol.  iii.) :  We  must  needs 
confess  that  God  is  happiness  itself. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  happiness  is  the  supreme  good.  But  it 
belongs  to  God  to  be  the  supreme  good.  Since,  then,  there 
are  not  several  supreme  goods,  it  seems  that  happiness  is  the 
same  as  God. 

34 


WHAT  IS  HAPPINESS  35 

Obj.  3.  Further,  happiness  is  the  last  end,  to  which  man's 
will  tends  naturally.  But  man's  will  should  tend  to  nothing 
else  as  an  end,  but  to  God,  Who  alone  is  to  be  enjoyed,  as 
Augustine  says  {De  Doctr.  Christ,  i.).  Therefore  happiness  is 
the  same  as  God. 

On  the  contrary,  Nothing  made  is  uncreated.  But  man's 
happiness  is  something  made;  because  according  to  Augus- 
tine (De  Doctr.  Christ,  i.) :  Those  things  are  to  he  enjoyed, 
which  make  us  ha-ppy.  Therefore  happiness  is  not  some- 
thing uncreated. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  8;  Q.  II.,  A.  7), 
our  end  is  twofold.  First,  there  is  the  thing  itself  which  we 
desire  to  attain:  thus  for  the  miser,  the  end  is  money. 
Secondly  there  is  the  attainment  or  possession,  the  use  or 
enjoyment  of  the  thing  desired;  thus  we  may  say  that  the 
end  of  the  miser  is  the  possession  of  money;  and  the  end  of 
the  intemperate  man  is  to  enjoy  something  pleasurable.  In 
the  first  sense,  then,  man's  last  end  is  the  uncreated  good, 
namely  God,  Who  alone,  of  His  infinite  goodness  can  per- 
fectly satisfy  man's  will.  But  in  the  second  way,  man's  last 
end  is  something  created,  existing  in  him,  and  this  is  nothing 
else  than  the  attainment  or  enjoyment  of  the  last  end. 
Now  the  last  end  is  called  happiness.  If,  therefore,  we 
consider  man's  happiness  in  its  cause  or  object,  then  it  is 
something  uncreated;  but  if  we  consider  it  as  to  the  very 
essence  of  happiness,  then  it  is  something  created. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  God  is  happiness  by  His  Essence:  for  He 
is  happy  not  by  acquisition  or  participation,  but  by  His 
Essence.  On  the  other  hand,  men  are  happy,  as  Boethius 
says  (loc.  cit.)  by  participation;  just  as  they  are  called  gods, 
by  participation.  And  this  participation  of  happiness,  in 
respect  of  which  man  is  said  to  be  happy,  is  something 
created. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Happiness  is  called  man's  supreme  good, 
because  it  is  the  attainment  or  enjoyment  of  the  supreme 
good. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Happiness  is  said  to  be  the  last  end,  in  the 
same  way  as  the  attainment  of  the  end  is  called  the  end. 


36  QUESTION  III 

Second  Article, 
whether  happiness  is  an  operation  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  happiness  is  not  an  operation. 
For  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  vi.  22)  :  You  have  your  fruit 
unto  sanctifi cation,  and  the  end,  life  everlasting.  But  hfe  is 
not  an  operation,  but  the  very  being  of  living  things. 
Therefore  the  last  end,  which  is  happiness,  is  not  an 
operation. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Boethius  says  {De  Consol.  iii.)  that  happi- 
ness is  a  state  made  perfect  by  the  aggregate  of  all  good  things. 
But  state  does  not  indicate  operation.  Therefore  happi- 
ness is  not  an  operation. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  happiness  signifies  something  existing  in 
the  happy  one :  since  it  is  man's  final  perfection.  But  the 
meaning  of  operation  does  not  imply  anything  existing  in 
the  operator,  but  rather  something  proceeding  therefrom. 
Therefore  happiness  is  not  an  operation. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  happiness  remains  in  the  happy  one. 
Now  operation  does  not  remain,  but  passes.  Therefore 
happiness  is  not  an  operation. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  to  one  man  there  is  one  happiness.  But 
operations  are  many.  Therefore  happiness  is  not  an 
operation. 

Obj.  6.  Further,  happiness  is  in  the  happy  one  uninter- 
ruptedly. But  human  operation  is  often  interrupted;  for 
instance,  by  sleep,  or  some  other  occupation,  or  by  cessa- 
tion.    Therefore  happiness  is  not  an  operation. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  i.)  that 
happiness  is  an  operation  according  to  perfect  virtue. 

I  answer  that.  In  so  far  as  man's  happiness  is  something 
created,  existing  in  him,  we  must  needs  say  that  it  is  an 
operation.  For  happiness  is  man's  supreme  perfection. 
Now  each  thing  is  perfect  in  so  far  as  it  is  actual;  since 
potentiality  without  act  is  imperfect.  Consequently  happi- 
ness must  consist  in  man's  last  act.  But  it  is  evident  that 
operation  is  the  last   act    of  the  operator,   wherefore  the 


WHAT  IS  HAPPINESS  37 

Philosopher  calls  it  second  act  [De  Anima  ii.) :  because  that 
which  has  a  form  can  be  potentially  operating,  just  as  he 
who  knows  is  potentially  considering.  And  hence  it  is  that 
in  other  things,  too,  each  one  is  said  to  be  for  its  operation 
{De  Coelo  ii.).  Therefore  man's  happiness  must  of  necessity 
consist  in  an  operation. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Life  is  taken  in  two  senses.  First  for  the 
very  being  of  the  living.  And  thus  happiness  is  not  life :  since 
it  has  been  shown  (Q.  II.,  A.  5)  that  the  being  of  a  man,  no 
matter  in  what  it  may  consist,  is  not  that  man's  happiness; 
for  of  God  alone  is  it  true  that  His  Being  is  His  happiness. 
Secondly,  life  means  the  operation  of  the  living,  by  which 
operation  the  principle  of  life  is  made  actual :  thus  we  speak 
of  active  and  contemplative  life,  or  of  a  life  of  pleasure. 
And  in  this  sense  eternal  life  is  said  to  be  the  last  end,  as  is 
clear  from  John  xvii.  3:  This  is  life  everlasting,  that  they 
may  know  Thee,  the  only  true  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Boethius,  in  defining  happiness,  considered 
happiness  in  general:  for  considered  thus  it  is  the  perfect 
common  good  ;  and  he  signified  this  by  saying  that  happiness 
is  a  state  made  perfect  by  the  aggregate  of  all  good  things,  thus 
impl3dng  that  the  state  of  a  happy  man  consists  in  possessing 
the  perfect  good.  But  Aristotle  expressed  the  very  essence 
of  happiness,  showing  by  what  man  is  established  in  this 
state,  and  that  it  is  by  some  kind  of  operation.  And  so  it 
is  that  he  proves  happiness  to  be  the  perfect  good  [Ethic,  i.). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  stated  in  Metaph.  ix.  action  is  twofold. 
One  proceeds  from  the  agent  into  outward  matter,  such  as 
to  hum  and  to  cut.  And  such  an  operation  cannot  be  happi- 
ness: for  such  an  operation  is  an  action  and  a  perfection, 
not  of  the  agent,  but  rather  of  the  patient,  as  is  stated  in  the 
same  passage.  The  other  is  an  action  that  remains  in  the 
agent,  such  as  to  feel,  to  understand,  and  to  will :  and  such 
an  action  is  a  perfection  and  an  act  of  the  agent.  And  such 
an  operation  can  be  happiness. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  Since  happiness  signifies  some  final  per- 
fection; according  as  various  things  capable  of  happiness 
can  attain  to  various  degrees  of  perfection,  so  must  there 


38  QUESTION  III 

be  various  meanings  applied  to  happiness.  For  in  God 
there  is  happiness  essentially ;  since  His  very  Being  is  His 
operation,  whereby  He  enjoys  no  other  than  Himself.  In 
the  happy  angels,  the  final  perfection  is  in  respect  of  some 
operation,  by  which  they  are  united  to  the  Uncreated  Good : 
and  this  operation  of  theirs  is  one  only  and  everlasting. 
But  in  men,  according  to  their  present  state  of  life,  the  final 
perfection  is  in  respect  of  an  operation  whereby  man  is  united 
to  God:  but  this  operation  neither  can  be  continual,  nor, 
consequently,  is  it  one  only,  because  operation  is  multiplied 
by  being  discontinued.  And  for  this  reason  in  the  present 
state  of  life,  perfect  happiness  cannot  be  attained  by  man. 
Wherefore  the  Philosopher,  in  placing  man's  happiness  in 
this  life  [Ethic,  i.),  says  that  it  is  imperfect,  and  after  a  long 
discussion,  concludes:  We  call  men  happy,  hut  only  as  men. 
But  God  has  promised  us  perfect  happiness,  when  we  shall 
be  as  the  angels  .  .  .  in  heaven  (Matth.  xxii.  30) . 

Consequently  in  regard  to  this  perfect  happiness,  the 
objection  fails:  because  in  that  state  of  happiness,  man's 
mind  will  be  united  to  God  by  one,  continual,  everlasting 
operation.  But  in  the  present  life,  in  as  far  as  we  fall  short 
of  the  unity  and  continuity  of  that  operation,  so  do  we  fall 
short  of  perfect  happiness.  Nevertheless  it  is  a  participa- 
tion of  happiness :  and  so  much  the  greater,  as  the  operation 
can  be  more  continuous  and  more  one.  Consequently  the 
active  life,  which  is  busy  with  many  things,  has  less  of 
happiness  than  the  contemplative  life,  which  is  busied  with 
one  thing,  i.e.,  the  contemplation  of  truth.  And  if  at  any 
time  man  is  not  actually  engaged  in  this  operation,  yet  since 
he  can  always  easily  turn  to  it,  and  since  he  ordains  the 
very  cessation,  by  sleeping  or  occupying  himself  otherwise, 
to  the  aforesaid  occupation,  the  latter  seems,  as  it  were, 
continuous.  From  these  remarks  the  replies  to  Objections  5 
and  6  are  evident. 


WHAT  IS  HAPPINESS  39 


Third  Article. 

whether  happiness  is  an  operation  of  the  sensitive 
part,  or  of  the  intellective  part  only  ? 

V/e  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  happiness  consists  in  an  opera- 
tion of  the  senses  also.  For  there  is  no  more  excellent 
operation  in  man  than  that  of  the  senses,  except  the  intel- 
lective operation.  But  in  us  the  intellective  operation 
depends  on  the  sensitive :  since  we  cannot  understand  without 
a  phantasm  (De  Anima  iii.).  Therefore  happiness  consists 
in  an  operation  of  the  senses  also. 

Ohj .  2.  Further,  Boethius  says  [De  Consol.  iii.)  that  happi- 
ness is  a  state  made  perfect  by  the  aggregate  of  all  good  things. 
But  some  goods  are  sensible,  which  we  attain  by  the  opera- 
tion of  the  senses.  Therefore  it  seems  that  the  operation 
of  the  senses  is  needed  for  happiness. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  happiness  is  the  perfect  good,  as  we  find 
proved  in  Ethic,  i. :  which  would  not  be  true,  were  not  man 
perfected  thereby  in  all  his  parts.  But  some  parts  of  the 
soul  are  perfected  by  sensitive  operations.  Therefore  sensi- 
tive operation  is  required  for  happiness. 

On  the  contrary,  Irrational  animals  have  the  sensitive 
operation  in  common  with  us :  but  they  have  not  happiness 
in  common  with  us.  Therefore  happiness  does  not  consist 
in  a  sensitive  operation. 

I  answer  that,  A  thing  may  belong  to  happiness  in  three 
ways:  (i)  essentially,  (2)  antecedently,  (3)  consequently. 
Now  the  operation  of  sense  cannot  belong  to  happiness 
essentially.  For  man's  happiness  consists  essentially  in  his 
being  united  to  the  Uncreated  Good,  Which  is  his  last  end, 
as  shown  above  (A.  i) :  to  Which  man  cannot  be  united  by 
an  operation  of  his  senses.  Again,  in  like  manner,  because, 
as  shown  above  (Q.  II.,  A.  5),  man's  happiness  does  not 
consist  in  goods  of  the  body,  which  goods  alone,  however, 
we  attain  through  the  operation  of  the  senses. 

Nevertheless  the  operations  of  the  senses  can  belong  to 


40  QUESTION  III 

happiness,  both  antecedently  and  consequently:  antece- 
dently, in  respect  of  imperfect  happiness,  such  as  can  be  had 
in  this  life,  since  the  operation  of  the  intellect  demands  a 
previous  operation  of  the  sense; — consequently,  in  that 
perfect  happiness  which  we  await  in  heaven ;  because  at  the 
resurrection, /rom  the  very  happiness  of  the  soul,  as  Augustine 
says  [Ep.  ad  Dioscor.)  the  body  and  the  bodily  senses  will 
receive  a  certain  overflow,  so  as  to  be  perfected  in  their  opera- 
tions ;  a  point  which  will  be  explained  farther  on  when  we 
treat  of  the  resurrection  (Suppl.  QQ.  LXXXII.-LXXXV.). 
But  then  the  operation  whereby  man's  mind  is  united  to 
God  will  not  depend  on  the  senses. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  This  objection  proves  that  the  operation 
of  the  senses  is  required  antecedently  for  imperfect  happi- 
ness, such  as  can  be  had  in  this  life. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Perfect  happiness,  such  as  the  angels  have, 
includes  the  aggregate  of  all  good  things,  by  being  united  to 
the  universal  source  of  all  good;  not  that  it  requires  each 
individual  good.  But  in  this  imperfect  happiness,  we  need 
the  aggregate  of  those  goods  that  suffice  for  the  most  perfect 
operation  of  this  life. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  perfect  happiness  the  entire  man  is 
perfected,  in  the  lower  part  of  his  nature,  by  an  overflow  from 
the  higher.  But  in  the  imperfect  happiness  of  this  life,  it  is 
otherwise ;  we  advance  from  the  perfection  of  the  lower  part 
to  the  perfection  of  the  higher  part. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether,  if  happiness  is  in  the  intellective  part,  it 
is  an  operation  of  the  intellect  or  of  the  will  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  happiness  consists  in  an  act  of 
the  will.  For  Augustine  says  {De  Civ.  Dei.  xix.) ,  that  man's 
happiness  consists  in  peace;  wherefore  it  is  written  (Ps. 
cxlvii.  3) :  Who  hath  placed  peace  in  thy  end  (Douay, — borders) . 
But  peace  pertains  to  the  will.  Therefore  man's  happiness 
is  in  the  will. 


WHAT  IS  HAPPINESS  41 

Obj.  2.  Further,  happiness  is  the  supreme  good.  But 
good  is  the  object  of  the  will.  Therefore  happiness  consists 
in  an  operation  of  the  will. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  last  end  corresponds  to  the  first 
mover:  thus  the  last  end  of  the  whole  army  is  victory, 
which  is  the  end  of  the  general,  who  moves  all  the  men.  But 
the  first  mover  in  regard  to  operations  is  the  wiU :  because  it 
moves  the  other  powers,  as  we  shall  state  further  on  (Q.  IX., 
AA.  I,  3).     Therefore  happiness  regards  the  will. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  if  happiness  be  an  operation,  it  must 
needs  be  man's  most  excellent  operation.  But  the  love  of 
God,  which  is  an  act  of  the  will,  is  a  more  excellent  operation 
than  knowledge,  which  is  an  operation  of  the  intellect,  as  the 
Apostle  declares  (i  Cor.  xiii.).  Therefore  it  seems  that 
happiness  consists  in  an  act  of  the  will. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  xiii.)  that 
haj)j)y  is  he  who  has  whatever  he  desires,  and  desires  nothing 
amiss.  And  a  little  further  on  he  adds :  He  is  almost  happy 
who  desires  well,  whatever  he  desires  :  for  good  things  make  a 
man  happy,  and  such  a  man  already  possesses  some  good — 
i.e.,  a  good  will.  Therefore  happiness  consists  in  an  act  of 
the  will. 

On  the  contrary.  Our  Lord  said  (John  xvii.  3):  This  is 
eternal  life  :  that  they  may  know  Thee,  the  only  true  God.  Now 
eternal  life  is  the  last  end,  as  stated  above  (A.  2  ad  i). 
Therefore  man's  happiness  consists  in  the  knowledge  of  God, 
which  is  an  act  of  the  intellect. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  II.,  A.  6)  two  things  are 
needed  for  happiness :  one,  which  is  the  essence  of  happiness : 
the  other,  that  is,  as  it  were,  its  proper  accident,  i.e.,  the 
delight  connected  with  it.  I  say,  then,  that  as  to  the  very 
essence  of  happiness,  it  is  impossible  for  it  to  consist  in  an 
act  of  the  will.  For  it  is  evident  from  what  has  been  said 
(AA.  I,  2;  Q.  II.,  A.  7)  that  happiness  is  the  attainment  of 
the  last  end.  But  the  attainment  of  the  end  does  not  consist 
in  the  very  act  of  the  will.  For  the  will  is  directed  to  the 
end,  both  absent,  when  it  desires  it ;  and  present,  when  it  is 
delighted  by  resting  therein.     Now  it  is  evident  that  the 


42  QUESTION  III 

desire  itself  of  the  end  is  not  the  attainment  of  the  end,  but 
is  a  movement  towards  the  end:  while  delight  comes  to  the 
will  from  the  end  being  present;  and  not  conversely,  is  a 
thing  made  present,  by  the  fact  that  the  will  delights  in  it. 
Therefore,  that  the  end  be  present  to  him  who  desires  it, 
must  be  due  to  something  else  than  an  act  of  the  will. 

This  is  evidently  the  case  in  regard  to  sensible  ends.  For 
if  the  acquisition  of  money  were  through  an  act  of  the 
will,  the  covetous  man  would  have  it  from  the  very  moment 
that  he  wished  for  it.  But  at  that  moment  it  is  far  from 
him;  and  he  attains  it,  by  grasping  it  in  his  hand,  or  in  some 
like  manner;  and  then  he  delights  in  the  money  got.  And 
so  it  is  with  an  intelligible  end.  For  at  first  we  desire  to 
attain  an  intelligible  end;  we  attain  it,  through  its  being 
made  present  to  us  by  an  act  of  the  intellect;  and  then  the 
delighted  will  rests  in  the  end  when  attained. 

So,  therefore,  the  essence  of  happiness  consists  in  an  act 
of  the  intellect :  but  the  delight  that  results  from  happiness 
pertains  to  the  will.  In  this  sense  Augustine  says  [Conf.  x.) 
that  happiness  is  joy  in  truth,  because,  to  wit,  joy  itself  is  the 
consummation  of  happiness. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Peace  pertains  to  man's  last  end,  not  as 
though  it  were  the  very  essence  of  happiness;  but  because 
it  is  antecedent  and  consequent  thereto:  antecedent,  in  so 
far  as  all  those  things  are  removed  which  disturb  and  hinder 
man  in  attaining  the  last  end:  consequent,  inasmuch  as, 
when  man  has  attained  his  last  end,  he  remains  at  peace, 
his  desire  being  at  rest. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  will's  first  object  is  not  its  act:  just  as 
neither  is  the  first  object  of  the  sight,  vision,  but  a  visible 
thing.  Wherefore,  from  the  very  fact  that  happiness 
belongs  to  the  will,  as  the  will's  first  object,  it  follows  that 
it  does  not  belong  to  it  as  its  act. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  intellect  apprehends  the  end  before  the 
will  does:  yet  motion  towards  the  end  begins  in  the  will. 
And  therefore  to  the  will  belongs  that  which  last  of  all  follows 
the  attainment  of  the  end,  viz.,  dehght  or  enjoyment. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  Love  ranks  above  knowledge  in  moving, 


WHAT  IS  HAPPINESS  43 

but  knowledge  precedes  love  in  attaining:  for  naught  is  loved 
save  what  is  known,  as  Augustine  says  {De  Trin.  x.).  Conse- 
quently we  first  attain  an  intelligible  end  by  an  act  of  the 
intellect;  just  as  we  first  attain  a  sensible  end  by  an  act  of 
sense. 

Reply  Obj.  5.  He  who  has  whatever  he  desires,  is  happy, 
because  he  has  what  he  desires :  and  this  indeed  is  by  some- 
thing other  than  the  act  of  his  will.  But  to  desire  nothing 
amiss  is  needed  for  happiness,  as  a  necessary  disposition 
thereto.  And  a  good  will  is  reckoned  among  the  good  things 
which  make  a  man  happy,  forasmuch  as  it  is  an  inclination 
of  the  will :  just  as  a  movement  is  reduced  to  the  genus  of  its 
terminus,  for  instance,  alteration  to  the  genus  quality. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  happiness  is  an  operation  of  the  speculative, 
or  of  the  practical  intellect  ? 

V/e  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : —    , 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  happiness  is  an  operation  of  the 
practical  intellect.  For  the  end  of  every  creature  consists 
in  becoming  like  God.  But  man  is  like  God,  by  his  practical 
intellect,  which  is  the  cause  of  things  understood,  rather  than 
by  his  speculative  intellect,  which  derives  its  knowledge 
from  things.  Therefore  man's  happiness  consists  in  an 
operation  of  the  practical  intellect  rather  than  of  the 
speculative. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  happiness  is  man's  perfect  good.  But 
the  practical  intellect  is  ordained  to  the  good  rather  than 
the  speculative  intellect,  which  is  ordained  to  the  true. 
Hence  we  are  said  to  be  good,  in  reference  to  the  perfection  of 
the  practical  intellect,  but  not  in  reference  to  the  perfection 
of  the  speculative  intellect,  according  to  which  we  are  said 
to  be  knowing  or  understanding.  Therefore  man's  happi- 
ness consists  in  an  act  of  the  practical  intellect  rather  than  of 
the  speculative. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  happiness  is  a  good  of  man  himself.  But 
the  speculative  intellect  is  more  concerned  with  things  outside 


44  QUESTION  III 

man ;  whereas  the  practical  intellect  is  concerned  with  things 
belonging  to  man  himself,  viz.,  his  operations  and  passions. 
Therefore  man's  happiness  consists  in  an  operation  of  the 
practical  intellect  rather  than  of  the  speculative. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Trin,  i.)  that  con- 
templation is  promised  us,  as  being  the  goal  of  all  our  actions, 
and  the  everlasting  perfection  of  our  joys. 

I  answer  that.  Happiness  consists  in  an  operation  of  the 
speculative  rather  than  of  the  practical  intellect.  This  is 
evident  for  three  reasons.  First,  because  if  man's  happiness 
is  an  operation,  it  must  needs  be  man's  highest  operation. 
Now  man's  highest  operation  is  that  of  his  highest  power  in 
respect  of  its  highest  object:  and  his  highest  power  is  the 
intellect,  whose  highest  object  is  the  Divine  Good,  which  is 
the  object,  not  of  the  practical,  but  of  the  speculative 
intellect.  Consequently  happiness  consists  principally  in 
such  an  operation,  viz.,  in  the  contemplation  of  Divine 
things.  And  since  that  seems  to  he  each  man's  self,  which  is 
best  in  him,  according  to  Ethic,  ix.  and  x.,  therefore  such  an 
operation  is  most  proper  to  man  a,nd  most  delightful 
to  him. 

Secondly,  it  is  evident  from  the  fact  that  contemplation 
is  sought  principally  for  its  own  sake.  But  the  act  of  the 
practical  intellect  is  not  sought  for  its  own  sake  but  for  the 
sake  of  action :  and  these  very  actions  are  ordained  to  some 
end.  Consequently  it  is  evident  that  the  last  end  cannot 
consist  in  the  active  life,  which  pertains  to  the  practical 
intellect. 

Thirdly,  it  is  again  evident,  from  the  fact  that  in  the 
contemplative  life  man  has  something  in  common  with  things 
above  him,  viz.,  with  God  and  the  angels,  to  whom  he  is  made 
like  by  happiness.  But  in  things  pertaining  to  the  active 
life,  other  animals  also  have  something  in  common  with  man, 
although  imperfectly. 

Therefore  the  last  and  perfect  happiness,  which  we  await 
in  the  life  to  come,  consists  entirely  in  contemplation.  But 
imperfect  happiness,  such  as  can  be  had  here,  consists  first 
and  principally  in  contemplation,  but  secondarily,  in  an 


WHAT  IS  HAPPINESS  45 

operation  of  the  practical  intellect  directing  human  actions 
and  passions,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  x. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  asserted  likeness  of  the  practical  intellect 
to  God  is  one  of  proportion ;  that  is  to  say,  by  reason  of  its 
standing  in  relation  to  what  it  knows,  as  God  does  to  what 
He  knows.  But  the  likeness  of  the  speculative  intellect  to 
God  is  one  of  union  and  information  ;  which  is  a  much  greater 
likeness. — And  yet  it  may  be  answered  that,  in  regard  to  the 
principal  thing  known,  which  is  His  Essence,  God  has  not 
practical  but  merely  speculative  knowledge. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  practical  intellect  is  ordained  to  good 
which  is  outside  of  it :  but  the  speculative  intellect  has  good 
within  it,  viz.,  the  contemplation  of  truth.  And  if  this 
good  be  perfect,  the  whole  man  is  perfected  and  made  good 
thereby:  such  a  good  the  practical  intellect  has  not;  but  it 
directs  man  thereto. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  argument  would  hold,  if  man  himself 
were  his  own  last  end ;  for  then  the  consideration  and  direc- 
tion of  his  actions  and  passions  would  be  his  happiness. 
But  since  man's  last  end  is  something  outside  of  him,  to 
wit,  God,  to  Whom  we  reach  out  by  an  operation  of  the 
speculative  intellect;  therefore  man's  happiness  consists  in 
an  operation  of  the  speculative  intellect  rather  than  of  the 
practical  intellect. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  happiness  consists  in  the  consideration  of 
speculative  sciences  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man's  happiness  consists  in  the 
consideration  of  speculative  sciences.  For  the  Philosopher 
says  (Ethic,  i.)  that  happiness  is  an  operation  according  to 
perfect  virtue.  And  in  distinguishing  the  virtues,  he  gives 
no  more  than  these — knowledge,  wisdom  and  understanding, 
which  all  belong  to  the  consideration  of  speculative  sciences. 
Therefore  man's  final  happiness  consists  in  the  consideration 
of  speculative  sciences. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  that  which  all  desire  for  its  own  sake, 


46  QUESTION  III 

seems  to  be  man's  final  happiness.  Now  such  is  the  con- 
sideration of  speculative  sciences;  because,  as  stated  in 
Metaph.  i.,  all  men  naturally  desire  to  know  ;  and,  a  little 
farther  on,  it  is  stated  that  speculative  sciences  are  sought 
for  their  own  sakes.  Therefore  happiness  consists  in  the 
consideration  of  speculative  sciences. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  happiness  is  man's  final  perfection.  Now 
everything  is  perfected,  according  as  it  is  reduced  from 
potentiality  to  act.  But  the  human  intellect  is  reduced  to 
act  by  the  consideration  of  speculative  sciences.  Therefore 
it  seems  that  in  the  consideration  of  these  sciences,  man's 
final  happiness  consists. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Jer.  ix.  23):  Let  not  the 
wise  man  glory  in  his  wisdom  :  and  this  is  said  in  reference 
to  speculative  sciences.  Therefore  man's  final  happiness 
does  not  consist  in  the  consideration  of  these. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  2  ad  4),  man's  happi- 
ness is  twofold,  one  perfect,  the  other  imperfect.  And  by 
perfect  happiness  we  are  to  understand  that  which  attains 
to  the  true  notion  of  happiness ;  and  by  imperfect  happiness 
that  which  does  not  attain  thereto,  but  partakes  of  some 
particular  likeness  of  happiness.  Thus  perfect  prudence  is 
in  man,  with  whom  is  the  idea  of  things  to  be  done;  while 
imperfect  prudence  is  in  certain  irrational  animals,  who  are 
possessed  of  certain  particular  instincts  in  respect  of  works 
similar  to  works  of  prudence. 

Accordingly  perfect  happiness  cannot  consist  essentially 
in  the  consideration  of  speculative  sciences.  To  prove  this, 
we  must  observe  that  the  consideration  of  a  speculative 
science  does  not  extend  beyond  the  scope  of  the  principles 
of  that  science:  since  the  entire  science  is  virtually  con- 
tained in  its  principles.  Now  the  first  principles  of  specula- 
tive sciences  are  received  through  the  senses,  as  the  Philo- 
sopher clearly  states  at  the  beginning  of  the  Metaphysics 
and  at  the  end  of  the  Posterior  Analytics.  Wherefore  the 
entire  consideration  of  speculative  sciences  cannot  extend 
farther  than  knowledge  of  sensibles  can  lead.  Now  man's 
final  happiness,  which  is  his  final  perfection,  cannot  consist 


WHAT  IS  HAPPINESS  47 

in  the  knowledge  of  sensibles.  For  a  thing  is  not  perfected 
by  something  lower,  except  in  so  far  as  the  lower  partakes 
of  something  higher.  Now  it  is  evident  that  the  form  of  a 
stone  or  of  any  sensible,  is  lower  than  man.  Consequently 
the  intellect  is  not  perfected  by  the  form  of  a  stone,  as  such, 
but  inasmuch  as  it  partakes  of  a  certain  likeness  to  that 
which  is  above  the  human  intellect,  viz.,  the  intelligible 
light,  or  something  of  the  kind.  Now  whatever  is  by  some- 
thing else  is  reduced  to  that  which  is  of  itself.  Therefore 
man's  final  perfection  must  needs  be  through  knowledge  of 
something  above  the  human  intellect.  But  it  has  been 
shown  (Part  I.,  Q.  LXXXVIIL,  A.  2),  that  man  cannot 
acquire  through  sensibles,  the  knowledge  of  separate  sub- 
stances, which  are  above  the  human  intellect.  Consequently 
it  follows  that  man's  happiness  cannot  consist  in  the  con- 
sideration of  speculative  sciences.  However,  just  as  in 
sensible  forms  there  is  a  participation  of  the  higher  sub- 
stances, so  the  consideration  of  speculative  sciences  is  a 
certain  participation  of  true  and  perfect  happiness. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  In  his  book  on  Ethics  the  Philosopher  treats 
of  imperfect  happiness,  such  as  can  be  had  in  this  life,  as 
stated  above  (A.  2  ad  4). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Not  only  is  perfect  happiness  naturally 
desired,  but  also  any  likeness  or  participation  thereof. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Our  intellect  is  reduced  to  act,  in  a  fashion, 
by  the  consideration  of  speculative  sciences,  but  not  to  its 
final  and  perfect  act. 

Seventh  Article. 

whether  happiness  consists  in  the  knowledge  of 
separate  substances,  namely,  angels  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man's  happiness  consists  in  the 
knowledge  of  separate  substances,  namely,  angels.  For 
Gregory  says  in  a  homily  (xxvi.) :  It  avails  nothing  to  take 
part  in  the  feasts  of  men,  if  we  fail  to  take  part  in  the  feasts 
of  angels  ;  by  which  he  means  final  happiness.     But  we  can 


48  QUESTION  III 

take  part  in  the  feasts  of  the  angels  by  contemplating  them. 
Therefore  it  seems  that  man's  final  happiness  consists  in 
contemplating  the  angels. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  final  perfection  of  each  thing  is  for 
it  to  be  united  to  its  principle:  wherefore  a  circle  is  said  to 
be  a  perfect  figure,  because  its  beginning  and  end  coincide. 
But  the  beginning  of  human  knowledge  is  from  the  angels, 
by  whom  men  are  enlightened,  as  Dionysius  says  (Ccel. 
Hier.  iv.).  Therefore  the  perfection  of  the  human  intellect 
consists  in  contemplating  the  angels. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  each  nature  is  perfect,  when  united  to  a 
higher  nature;  just  as  the  final  perfection  of  a  body  is  to  be 
united  to  the  spiritual  nature.  But  above  the  intellect,  in 
the  natural  order,  are  the  angels.  Therefore  the  final  per- 
fection of  the  human  intellect  is  to  be  united  to  the  angels 
by  contemplation. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Jerem.  ix.  24) :  Let  him  that 
glorieth,  glory  in  this,  that  he  understandeth  and  knoweth  Me. 
Therefore  man's  final  glory  or  happiness,  consists  only  in 
the  knowledge  of  God. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  6),  man's  perfect 
happiness  consists  not  in  that  which  perfects  the  intellect 
by  some  participation,  but  in  that  which  is  so  by  its  essence. 
Now  it  is  evident  that  whatever  is  the  perfection  of  a  power 
is  so  in  so  far  as  the  proper  formal  object  of  that  power 
belongs  to  it.  Now  the  proper  object  of  the  intellect  is  the 
true.  Therefore  the  contemplation  of  whatever  has  par- 
ticipated truth,  does  not  perfect  the  intellect  with  its  final 
perfection.  Since,  therefore,  the  order  of  things  is  the  same 
in  being  and  in  truth  {Metaph.  ii.) ;  whatever  are  beings  by 
participation,  are  true  by  participation.  Now  angels  have 
being  by  participation:  because  in  God  alone  is  His  Being 
His  Essence,  as  shown  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XLIV.,  A.  i). 
It  follows  that  God  alone  is  truth  by  His  Essence,  and  that 
contemplation  of  Him  makes  man  perfectly  happy.  How- 
ever, there  is  no  reason  why  we  should  not  admit  a  certain 
imperfect  happiness  in  the  contemplation  of  the  angels ;  and 
higher  indeed  than  in  the  consideration  of  speculative  science. 


WHAT  IS  HAPPINESS  49 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  We  shall  take  part  in  the  feasts  of  the 
angels,  by  contemplating  not  only  the  angels,  but,  together 
with  them,  also  God  Himself. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  According  to  those  that  hold  human  souls 
to  be  created  by  the  angels,  it  seems  fitting  enough,  that 
man's  happiness  should  consist  in  the  contemplation  of  the 
angels,  in  the  union,  as  it  were,  of  man  with  his  beginning. 
But  this  is  erroneous,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XC, 
A.  3).  Wherefore  the  final  perfection  of  the  human  intellect, 
is  by  union  with  God,  Who  is  the  first  principle  both  of  the 
creation  of  the  soul  and  of  its  enlightenment.  Whereas  the 
angel  enlightens  as  a  minister,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part 
(Q.  CXL,  A.  2  ad  2).  Consequently,  by  his  ministration  he 
helps  man  to  attain  to  happiness;  but  he  is  not  the  object 
of  man's  happiness. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  lower  nature  may  reach  the  higher  in 
two  ways.  First,  according  to  a  degree  of  the  participating 
power:  and  thus  man's  final  perfection  will  consist  in  his 
attaining  to  a  contemplation  such  as  that  of  the  angels. 
Secondly,  as  the  object  is  attained  by  the  power :  and  thus 
the  final  perfection  of  each  power  is  to  attain  that  in  which 
is  found  the  fulness  of  its  formal  object. 

Eighth  Article. 

WHETHER   man's    HAPPINESS    CONSISTS   IN    THE   VISION    OF 
THE    DIVINE    ESSENCE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  man's  happiness  does  not  con- 
sist in  the  vision  of  the  Divine  Essence.  For  Dionysius 
says  (Myst.  Theol.  i.)  that  by  that  which  is  highest  in  his 
intellect,  man  is  united  to  God  as  to  something  altogether 
unknown.  But  that  which  is  seen  in  its  essence  is  not 
altogether  unknown.  Therefore  the  final  perfection  of  the 
intellect,  namely,  happiness,  does  not  consist  in  God  being 
seen  in  His  Essence. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  higher  perfection  belongs  to  the 
higher  nature.     But  to  see  His  own  Essence  is  the  perfec- 

II.  I  4 


50  QUESTION  III 

tion  proper  to  the  Divine  intellect.  Therefore  the  final 
perfection  of  the  human  intellect  does  not  reach  to  this, 
but  consists  in  something  less. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (i  John  iii.  2) :  When  He 
shall  appear,  we  shall  he  like  to  Rim  ;  and  (Vulg.,  because) 
we  shall  see  Kim  as  He  is. 

I  answer  that,  Final  and  perfect  happiness  can  consist  in 
nothing  else  than  the  vision  of  the  Divine  Essence.  To 
make  this  clear,  two  points  must  be  observed.  First,  that 
man  is  not  perfectly  happy,  so  long  as  something  remains 
for  him  to  desire  and  seek :  secondly,  that  the  perfection  of 
any  power  is  determined  by  the  nature  of  its  object.  Now 
the  object  of  the  intellect  is  what  a  thing  is,  i.e.,  the  essence 
of  a  thing,  according  to  De  Anima  iii.  Wherefore  the  in- 
tellect attains  perfection,  in  so  far  as  it  knows  the  essence 
of  a  thing.  If  therefore  an  intellect  know  the  essence  of 
some  effect,  whereby  it  is  not  possible  to  know  the  essence 
of  the  cause,  i.e.,  to  know  of  the  cause  what  it  is  ;  that 
intellect  cannot  be  said  to  reach  that  cause  simply,  although 
it  may  be  able  to  gather  from  the  effect  the  knowledge  that 
the  cause  is.  Consequently,  when  man  knows  an  effect, 
and  knows  that  it  has  a  cause,  there  naturally  remains  in 
man  the  desire  to  know  about  that  cause,  what  it  is.  And 
this  desire  is  one  of  wonder,  and  causes  inquiry,  as  is  stated 
in  the  beginning  of  the  Metaphysics.  For  instance,  if  a 
man,  knowing  the  eclipse  of  the  sun,  consider  that  it  must 
be  due  to  some  cause,  and  know  riot  what  that  cause  is, 
he  wonders  about  it,  and  from  wondering  proceeds  to 
inquire.  Nor  does  this  inquiry  cease  until  he  arrive  at  a 
knowledge  of  the  essence  of  the  cause. 

If  therefore  the  human  intellect,  knowing  the  essence  of 
some  created  effect,  knows  no  more  of  God  than  that  He  is  ; 
the  perfection  of  that  intellect  does  not  yet  reach  simply 
the  First  Cause,  but  there  remains  in  it  the  natural  desire 
to  seek  the  cause.  Wherefore  it  is  not  yet  perfectly  happy. 
Consequently,  for  perfect  happiness  the  intellect  needs  to 
reach  the  very  Essence  of  the  First  Cause.  And  thus  it 
will  have  its  perfection  through  union  with  God  as  with 


WHAT  IS  HAPPINESS  51 

that  object,  in  which  alone  man's  happiness  consists,  as 
stated  above  (AA.  i,  7;  Q.  II. ,  A.  8). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Dionysius  speaks  of  the  knowledge  of  way- 
farers journeying  towards  happiness. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  As  stated  above  (Q.  L,  A.  8),  the  end  has 
a  twofold  acceptation.  First,  as  to  the  thing  itself  which 
is  desired:  and  in  this  way,  the  same  thing  is  the  end  of  the 
higher  and  of  the  lower  nature,  and  indeed  of  all  things, 
as  stated  above  (ibid.).  Secondly,  as  to  the  attainment  of 
this  thing;  and  thus  the  end  of  the  higher  nature  is  dif- 
ferent from  that  of  the  lower,  according  to  their  respective 
habitudes  to  that  thing.  So  then  the  happiness  of  God, 
Who,  in  understanding  His  Essence,  comprehends  It,  is 
higher  than  that  of  a  man  or  angel  who  sees  It  indeed,  but 
comprehends  It  not. 


QUESTION  IV. 

OF  THOSE  THINGS  THAT  ARE  REQUIRED  FOR  HAPPINESS. 

{In  Eight  Articles.) 

We  have  now  to  consider  those  things  that  are  required  for 
happiness:  and  concerning  this  there  are  eight  points  of 
inquiry:  (i)  Whether  delight  is  required  for  happiness  ? 
(2)  Which  is  of  greater  account  in  happiness,  dehght  or 
vision  ?  (3)  Whether  comprehension  is  required  ? 
(4)  Whether  rectitude  of  the  will  is  required  ?  (5)  Whether 
the  body  is  necessary  for  man's  happiness  ?  (6)  Whether 
any  perfection  of  the  body  is  necessary  ?  (7)  Whether  any 
external  goods  are  necessary  ?  (8)  Whether  the  fellowship 
of  friends  is  necessary  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  delight  is  required  for  happiness  ? 

We  froceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  delight  is  not  required  for 
happiness.  For  Augustine  says  {De  Trin.  i.)  that  vision  is 
the  entire  reward  of  faith.  But  the  prize  or  reward  of  virtue 
is  happiness,  as  the  Philosopher  clearly  states  {Ethic,  i.). 
Therefore  nothing  besides  vision  is  required  for  happiness. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  happiness  is  the  most  self-sufficient  of  all 
goods,  as  the  Philosopher  declares  {Ethic,  i.).  But  that 
which  needs  something  else  is  not  self-sufficient.  Since 
then  the  essence  of  happiness  consists  in  seeing  God,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  III.,  A.  8);  it  seems  that  delight  is  not 
necessary  for  happiness. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  operation  of  bliss  or  happiness  should 

52 


WHAT  IS  REQUIRED  FOR  HAPPINESS  53 

be  unhindered  {Ethic,  vii.).  But  delight  hinders  the  opera- 
tion of  the  intellect:  since  it  destroys  the  estimate  of  pru- 
dence {Ethic,  vi.).  Therefore  deHght  is  not  necessary  for 
happiness. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {Conf.  x.)  that  happiness 
is  joy  in  truth. 

I  answer  that,  One  thing  may  be  necessary  for  another  in 
four  ways.  First,  as  a  preamble  and  preparation  to  it : 
thus  instruction  is  necessary  for  science.  Secondly,  as  per- 
fecting it:  thus  the  soul  is  necessary  for  the  life  of  the  body. 
Thirdly,  as  helping  it  from  without :  thus  friends  are  neces- 
sary for  some  undertaking.  Fourthly,  as  something  atten- 
dant on  it:  thus  we  might  say  that  heat  is  necessary  for  fire. 
And  in  this  way  delight  is  necessary  for  happiness.  For  it 
is  caused  by  the  appetite  being  at  rest  in  the  good  attained. 
Wherefore,  since  happiness  is  nothing  else  but  the  attain- 
ment of  the  Sovereign  Good,  it  cannot  be  without  con- 
comitant delight. 

Refly  Ohj.  i.  From  the  very  fact  that  a  reward  is  given 
to  anyone,  the  will  of  him  who  deserves  it  is  at  rest,  and  in 
this  consists  delight.  Consequently,  delight  is  included  in 
the  very  notion  of  reward. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  very  sight  of  God  causes  delight.  Con- 
sequently, he  who  sees  God  cannot  need  delight. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Delight  that  is  attendant  upon  the  opera- 
tion of  the  intellect  does  not  hinder  it,  rather  does  it  per- 
fect it,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  x. :  since  what  we  do  with  delight, 
we  do  with  greater  care  and  perseverance.  On  the  other 
hand,  delight  which  is  extraneous  to  the  operation  is  a 
hindrance  thereto: — sometimes  by  distracting  the  atten- 
tion; because,  as  already  observed,  we  are  more  attentive 
to  those  things  that  delight  us ;  and  when  we  are  very  atten- 
tive to  one  thing,  we  must  needs  be  less  attentive  to  another: 
— sometimes  on  account  of  opposition;  thus  a  sensual  de- 
light that  is  contrary  to  reason,  hinders  the  estimate  of 
prudence  more  than  it  hinders  the  estimate  of  the  specula- 
tive intellect. 


54  QUESTION  TV 


Second  Article, 
whether  in  happiness  vision  ranks  before  delight  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  in  happiness,  vision  ranks 
before  deHght.  For  delight  is  the  perfection  of  operation 
(Ethic.  X.).  But  perfection  ranks  before  the  thing  perfected. 
Therefore  dehght  ranks  before  the  operation  of  the  intellect, 
i.e.,  vision. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  that  by  reason  of  which  a  thing  is  desir- 
able, is  yet  more  desirable.  But  operations  are  desired  on 
account  of  the  delight  they  afford:  hence,  too,  nature  has 
adjusted  delight  to  those  operations  which  are  necessary 
for  the  preservation  of  the  individual  and  of  the  species, 
lest  animals  should  disregard  such  operations.  Therefore, 
in  happiness,  delight  ranks  before  the  operation  of  the 
intellect,  which  is  vision. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  vision  corresponds  to  faith;  while  delight 
or  enjoyment  corresponds  to  charity.  But  charity  ranks 
before  faith,  as  the  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  xiii.  13).  Therefore 
dehght  or  enjoyment  ranks  before  vision. 

On  the  contrary,  The  cause  is  greater  than  its  effect.  But 
vision  is  the  cause  of  delight.  Therefore  vision  ranks  before 
delight. 

I  answer  that,  The  Philosopher  discusses  this  question  in 
the  tenth  book  of  Ethics,  and  leaves  it  unsolved.  But  if  one 
consider  the  matter  carefully,  the  operation  of  the  intellect 
which  is  vision,  must  needs  rank  before  delight.  For  delight 
consists  in  a  certain  repose  of  the  will.  Now  that  the  will 
finds  rest  in  anything,  can  only  be  on  account  of  the  good- 
ness of  that  thing  in  which  it  reposes.  If  therefore  the  will 
reposes  in  an  operation,  the  will's  repose  is  caused  by  the 
goodness  of  the  operation.  Nor  does  the  will  seek  good  for 
the  sake  of  repose ;  for  thus  the  very  act  of  the  will  would  be 
the  end,  which  has  been  disproved  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  1  ad  2; 
Q.  III.,  A.  4) :  but  it  seeks  to  be  at  rest  in  the  operation, 
because   that   operation -is   its   good.     Consequently   it   is 


WHAT  IS  REQUIRED  FOR  HAPPINESS         55 

evident  that  the  operation  in  which  the  will  reposes  ranks 
before  the  resting  of  the  will  therein. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  the  Philosopher  says  [ibid.)  delight 
perfects  operation  as  vigour  perfects  youth,  because  it  is  a 
result  of  youth.  Consequently  delight  is  a  perfection 
attendant  upon  vision;  but  not  a  perfection  whereby  vision 
is  made  perfect  in  its  own  species. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  apprehension  of  the  senses  does  not 
attain  to  the  universal  good,  but  to  some  particular  good 
which  is  delightful.  And  consequently,  according  to  the 
sensitive  appetite  which  is  in  animals,  operations  are  sought 
for  the  sake  of  delight.  But  the  intellect  apprehends  the 
universal  good,  the  attainment  of  which  results  in  delight: 
wherefore  its  purpose  is  directed  to  good  rather  than  to 
delight.  Hence  it  is  that  the  Divine  intellect,  which  is  the 
Author  of  nature,  adjusted  delights  to  operations  on  account 
of  the  operations.  And  we  should  form  our  estimate  of 
things  not  simply  according  to  the  order  of  the  sensitive 
appetite,  but  rather  according  to  the  order  of  the  intellectual 
appetite. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Charity  does  not  seek  the  beloved  good  for 
the  sake  of  delight:  it  is  for  charity  a  consequence  that  it 
delights  in  the  good  gained  which  it  loves.  Thus  delight 
does  not  answer  to  charity  as  its  end,  but  vision  does, 
whereb}^  the  end  is  first  made  present  to  charity. 

Third  Article, 
whether  comprehension  is  necessary  for  happiness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  comprehension  is  not  necessary 
for  happiness.  For  Augustine  says  (Ad  Paulinam  de  Videndo 
Deum  ; — De  Verhis  Evang.,  Serm.  CXVII.):  To  reach  God 
with  the  mind  is  happiness,  to  comprehend  Him  is  impossible. 
Therefore  happiness  is  without  comprehension. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  happiness  is  the  perfection  of  man  as  to 
his  intellective  part,  wherein  there  are  no  other  powers 
than    the    intellect   and  will,  as   stated   in   the  First  Part 


56  QUESTION  IV 

(QQ.  LXXIX.  and  foil.).  But  the  intellect  is  sufficiently 
perfected  by  seeing  God,  and  the  will  by  enjoying  Him. 
Therefore  there  is  no  need  for  comprehension  as  a  third. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  happiness  consists  in  an  operation.  But 
operations  are  determined  by  their  objects:  and  there  are 
two  universal  objects,  the  true  and  the  good:  of  which  the 
true  corresponds  to  vision,  and  good  to  delight.  Therefore 
there  is  no  need  for  comprehension  as  a  third. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  ix.  24) :  So  run 
that  you  may  comprehend  (Douay, — obtain).  But  happi- 
ness is  the  goal  of  the  spiritual  race:  hence  he  says  (2  Tim. 
iv.  y,  8):  I  have  fought  a  good  fight,  I  have  finished  my  course, 
I  have  kept  the  faith  ;  as  to  the  rest  there  is  laid  up  for  me  a 
crown  of  justice.  Therefore  comprehension  is  necessary  for 
Happiness. 

/  answer  that,  Since  Happiness  consists  in  gaining  the  last 
end,  those  things  that  are  required  for  Happiness  must  be 
gathered  from  the  way  in  which  man  is  ordered  to  an  end. 
Now  man  is  ordered  to  an  intelligible  end  partly  through  his 
intellect,  and  partly  through  his  will : — through  his  intellect, 
in  so  far  as  a  certain  imperfect  knowledge  of  the  end  pre- 
exists in  the  intellect : — through  the  will,  first  by  love  which 
is  the  will's  first  movement  towards  anything;  secondly  by  a 
real  relation  of  the  lover  to  the  thing  beloved,  which  relation 
may  be  threefold.  For  sometimes  the  thing  beloved  is 
present  to  the  lover:  and  then  it  is  no  longer  sought  for. 
Sometimes  it  is  not  present,  and  it  is  impossible  to  attain  it : 
and  then,  too,  it  is  not  sought  for.  But  sometimes  it  is 
possible  to  attain  it,  yet  it  is  raised  above  the  capability  of 
the  attainer,  so  that  he  cannot  have  it  forthwith;  and  this  is 
the  relation  of  one  that  hopes,  to  that  which  he  hopes  for, 
and  this  relation  alone  causes  a  search  for  the  end.  To  these 
three,  there  are  a  corresponding  three  in  Happiness  itself. 
For  perfect  knowledge  of  the  end  corresponds  to  imperfect 
knowledge;  presence  of  the  end  corresponds  to  the  relation 
of  hope;  but  delight  in  the  end  now  present  results  from 
love,  as  already  stated  (A.  2  ad  3).  And  therefore  these 
three  must  concur  in  Happiness;  to  wit,  vision,  which  is 


WHAT  IS  REQUIRED  FOR  HAPPINESS  57 

perfect  knowledge  of  the  intelligible  end;  comprehension, 
which  implies  presence  of  the  end;  and  delight  or  enjoyment, 
which  implies  repose  of  the  lover  in  the  object  beloved. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Comprehension  is  twofold.  First,  inclusion 
of  the  comprehended  in  the  comprehensor ;  and  thus  what- 
ever is  comprehended  by  the  finite,  is  itself  finite.  Where- 
fore God  cannot  be  thus  comprehended  by  a  created 
intellect.  Secondly,  comprehension  means  nothing  but  the 
holding  of  something  already  present  and  possessed:  thus 
one  who  runs  after  another  is  said  to  comprehend*  him  when 
he  lays  hold  on  him.  And  in  this  sense  comprehension  is 
necessary  for  Happiness. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Just  as  hope  and  love  pertain  to  the  will, 
because  it  is  the  same  one  that  loves  a  thing,  and  that  tends 
towards  it  while  not  possessed;  so,  too,  comprehension  and 
delight  belong  to  the  will,  since  it  is  the  same  that  possesses 
a  thing  and  reposes  therein. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Comprehension  is  not  a  distinct  operation 
from  vision;  but  a  certain  relation  to  the  end  already  gained. 
Wherefore  even  vision  itself,  or  the  thing  seen,  inasmuch  as 
it  is  present,  is  the  object  of  comprehension. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  rectitude  of  the  will  is  necessary  for 

happiness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  rectitude  of  the  will  is  not 
necessary  for  Happiness.  For  Happiness  consists  essentially 
in  an  operation  of  the  intellect,  as  stated  above  (Q.  III., 
A.  4).  But  rectitude  of  the  will,  by  reason  of  which  men  are 
said  to  be  clean  of  heart,  is  not  necessary  for  the  perfect 
operation  of  the  intellect:  for  Augustine  says  (Retract,  i.) : 
/  do  not  approve  of  what  I  said  in  a  prayer  :  0  God,  Who  didst 
will  none  hut  the  clean  of  heart  to  know  the  truth.  For  it  can  he 
answered  that  many  who  are  not  clean  of  heart,  know  many  truths. 
Therefore  rectitude  of  the  will  is  not  necessary  for  Happiness. 
*  In  English  we  should  say  '  catch.' 


58  QUESTION  IV 

Obj.  2.  Further,  what  precedes  does  not  depend  on  what 
follows.  But  the  operation  of  the  intellect  precedes  the 
operation  of  the  will.  Therefore  Happiness,  which  is  the 
perfect  operation  of  the  intellect,  does  not  depend  on  recti- 
tude of  the  will. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  that  which  is  ordained  to  another  as  its 
end,  is  not  necessary,  when  the  end  is  already  gained;  as  a 
ship,  for  instance,  after  arrival  in  port.  But  rectitude  of  the 
will,  which  is  by  reason  of  virtue,  is  ordained  to  Happiness  as 
its  end.  Therefore,  Happiness  once  obtained,  rectitude  of 
the  will  is  no  longer  necessary. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Matth.  v.  8) :  Blessed  are  the 
clean  of  heart ;  for  they  shall  see  God :  and  (Heb.  xii.  14) : 
Follow  peace  with  all  men,  and  holiness  ;  without  which  no  man 
shall  see  God. 

I  answer  that.  Rectitude  of  the  will  is  necessary  for  Happi- 
ness both  antecedently  and  concomitantly.  Antecedently, 
because  rectitude  of  the  will  consists  in  being  duly  ordered 
to  the  last  end.  Now  the  end  in  comparison  to  what  is 
ordained  to  the  end  is  as  form  compared  to  matter.  Where- 
fore, just  as  matter  cannot  receive  a  form,  unless  it  be  duly 
disposed  thereto,  so  nothing  gains  an  end,  except  it  be  duly 
ordained  thereto.  And  therefore  none  can  obtain  Happi- 
ness, without  rectitude  of  the  will.  Concomitantly,  because 
as  stated  above  (Q.  III..  A.  8),  final  Happiness  consists  in 
the  vision  of  the  Divine  Essence,  Which  is  the  very  essence 
of  goodness.  So  that  the  will  of  him  who  sees  the  Essence  of 
God,  of  necessity,  loves,  whatever  he  loves,  in  subordination 
to  God;  just  as  the  will  of  him  who  sees  not  God's  Essence, 
of  necessity,  loves  whatever  he  loves,  under  that  common 
notion  of  good  which  he  knows.  And  this  is  precisely  what 
makes  the  will  right.  Wherefore  it  is  evident  that  Happiness 
cannot  be  without  a  right  will. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Augustine  is  speaking  of  the  knowledge  of 
that  truth  which  is  not  the  very  Essence  of  goodness. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Every  act  of  the  will  is  preceded  by  an  act 
of  the  intellect :  but  a  certain  act  of  the  will  precedes  a  certain 
act  of  the  intellect.     For  the  will  tends  to  the  final  act  of 


WHAT  IS  REQUIRED  FOR  HAPPINESS         59 

the  intellect  which  is  happiness.  And  consequently  right 
inclination  of  the  will  is  required  antecedently  for  happiness, 
just  as  the  arrow  must  take  a  right  course  in  order  to  strike 
the  target. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Not  everything  that  is  ordained  to  the  end, 
ceases  with  the  getting  of  the  end:  but  only  that  which 
involves  imperfection,  such  as  movement.  Hence  the 
instruments  of  movement  are  no  longer  necessary,  when  the 
end  has  been  gained:  but  the  due  order  to  the  end  is 
necessary. 

Fifth  Article. 

WHETHER  THE  BODY   IS   NECESSARY  FOR   MAN'S   HAPPINESS  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — ■ 

Objection  1  It  seems  that  the  body  is  necessary  for  Happi- 
ness. For  the  perfection  of  virtue  and  grace  presupposes 
the  perfection  of  nature.  But  Happiness  is  the  perfection 
of  virtue  and  grace.  Now  the  soul,  without  the  body,  has 
not  the  perfection  of  nature;  since  the  body  is  naturally  a 
part  of  human  nature,  and  every  part  is  imperfect,  while 
separated  from  its  whole.  Therefore  the  soul  cannot  be 
happy  without  the  body. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Happiness  is  a  perfect  operation,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  III.,  AA.  2,  5).  But  perfect  operation  follows 
perfect  being:  since  nothing  operates  except  in  so  far  as  it 
is  ah  actual  being.  Since,  therefore,  the  soul  has  not  perfect 
being,  while  it  is  separated  from  the  body,  just  as  neither  has 
a  part,  while  separate  from  its  whole;  it  seems  that  the  soul 
cannot  be  happy  without  the  body. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Happiness  is  the  perfection  of  man.  But 
the  soul,  without  the  body,  is  not  man.  Therefore  Happi- 
ness cannot  be  in  the  soul  separated  from  the  body. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  vii.), 
the  operation  of  hliss,  in  which  operation  happiness  consists, 
is  not  hindered.  But  the  operation  of  the  separate  soul  is 
hindered;  because,  as  Augustine  says  (Gen.  ad  lit.,  xii.),  the 
soul  has  a  natural  desire  to  rule  the  body,  the  result  of  which  is 
that  it  is  held  hack,  so  to  speak,  from  tending  with  all  its  might 


6o  QUESTION  IV 

to  the  heavenward  journey,  i.e.,  to  the  vision  of  the  Divine 
Essence.  Therefore  the  soul  cannot  be  happy  without  the 
body. 

Ohj.  5.  Further,  Happiness  is  the  sufficient  good  and  lulls 
desire.  But  this  cannot  be  said  of  the  separated  soul;  for  it 
yet  desires  to  be  united  to  the  body,  as  Augustine  says  [ihid.) . 
Therefore  the  soul  is  not  happy  while  separated  from  the 
body. 

Ohj.  6.  Further,  in  Happiness  man  is  equal  to  the  angels. 
But  the  soul  without  the  body  is  not  equal  to  the  angels, 
as  Augustine  says  {ihid.).     Therefore  it  is  not  happy. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Apoc.  xiv.  13):  Happy 
(Douay, — hlessed)  are  the  dead  who  die  in  the  Lord. 

I  answer  that,  Happiness  is  twofold;  the  one  is  imperfect 
and  is  had  in  this  life ;  the  other  is  perfect,  consisting  in  the 
vision  of  God.  Now  it  is  evident  that  the  body  is  necessary 
for  the  happiness  of  this  life.  For  the  happiness  of  this  life 
consists  in  an  operation  of  the  intellect,  either  speculative 
or  practical.  And  the  operation  of  the  intellect  in  this  life 
cannot  be  without  a  phantasm,  which  is  only  in  a  bodily 
organ,  as  was  shown  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  LXXXIV., 
AA.  6,  7).  Consequently  that  happiness  which  can  be  had 
in  this  life,  depends,  in  a  way,  on  the  body. 

But  as  to  perfect  Happiness,  which  consists  in  the  vision 
of  God,  some  have  maintained  that  it  is  not  possible  to  the 
soul  separated  from  the  body ;  and  have  said  that  the  souls 
of  saints,  when  separated  from  their  bodies,  do  not  attain 
to  that  Happiness  until  the  Day  of  Judgment,  when  they 
will  receive  their  bodies  back  again.  And  this  is  shown  to 
be  false,  both  by  authority  and  by  reason.  By  authority, 
since  the  Apostle  says  (2  Cor.  v.  6) :  While  we  are  in  the  hody> 
we  are  ahsent  from  the  Lord  ;  and  he  points  out  the  reason  of 
this  absence,  saying :  For  we  walk  hy  faith  and  not  hy  sight. 
Now  from  this  it  is  clear  that  so  long  as  we  walk  by  faith 
and  not  by  sight,  bereft  of  the  vision  of  the  Divine  Essence, 
we  are  not  present  to  the  Lord.  But  the  souls  of  the  saints, 
separated  from  their  bodies,  are  in  God's  presence;  wherefore 
the  text  continues:  But  we  are  confident  and  have  a  good  will 


WHAT  IS  REQUIRED  FOR  HAPPINESS         6i 

to -he  absent  .  .  .  from  the  body,  and  to  be  present  with  the  Lord. 
Whence  it  is  evident  that  the  souls  of  the  saints,  separated 
from  their  bodies,  walk  by  sight,  seeing  the  Essence  of  God, 
wherein  is  true  Happiness. 

Again  this  is  made  clear  by  reason.  For  the  intellect 
needs  not  the  body,  for  its  operation,  save  on  account  of  the 
phantasms,  wherein  it  looks  on  the  intelligible  truth,  as 
stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  LXXXIV.,  A.  7).  Now  it  is 
evident  that  the  Divine  Essence  cannot  be  seen  by  means  of 
phantasms,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XII.,  A.  3). 
Wherefore,  since  man's  perfect  Happiness  consists  in  the 
vision  of  the  Divine  Essence,  it  does  not  depend  on  the  body. 
Consequently,  without  the  body  the  soul  can  be  happy. 

We  must,  however,  notice  that  something  may  belong  to 
a  thing's  perfection  in  two  ways.  First,  as  constituting  the 
essence  thereof;  thus  the  soul  is  necessary  for  man's  per- 
fection. Secondly,  as  necessary  for  its  well-being:  thus, 
beauty  of  body  and  keenness  of  perception  belong  to  man's 
perfection.  Wherefore  though  the  body  does  not  belong  in 
the  first  way  to  the  perfection  of  human  Happiness,  yet  it 
does  in  the  second  way.  For  since  operation  depends  on  a 
thing's  nature,  the  more  perfect  is  the  soul  in  its  nature,  the 
more  perfectly  it  has  its  proper  operation,  wherein  its  happi- 
ness consists.  Hence  Augustine,  after  inquiring  (Gen.  ad  lit. 
xii.)  whether  that  perfect  Happiness  can  be  ascribed  to  the  souls 
of  the  dead  separated  from  their  bodies,  answers  that  they 
cannot  see  the  Unchangeable  Substance,  as  the  blessed  angels 
see  It ;  either  for  some  other  more  hidden  reason,  or  because 
they  have  a  natural  desire  to  rule  the  body. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Happiness  is  the  perfection  of  the  soul  on  the 
part  of  the  intellect,  in  respect  of  which  the  soul  transcends 
the  organs  of  the  body ;  but  not  according  as  the  soul  is  the 
natural  form  of  the  body.  Wherefore  the  soul  retains  that 
natural  perfection  in  respect  of  which  happiness  is  due  to  it, 
though  it  does  not  retain  that  natural  perfection  in  respect 
of  which  it  is  the  form  of  the  body. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  relation  of  the  soul  to  being  is  not  the 
same  as  that  of  other  parts :  for  the  being  of  the  whole  is  not 


62  QUESTION  IV 

that  of  any  individual  part :  wherefore,  either  the  part  ceases 
altogether  to  be,  when  the  whole  is  destroyed,  just  as  the 
parts  of  an  animal,  when  the  animal  is  destroyed ;  or,  if  they 
remain,  they  have  another  actual  being,  just  as  a  part  of  a 
line  has  another  being  from  that  of  the  whole  line.  But  the 
human  soul  retains  the  being  of  the  composite  after  the 
destruction  of  the  body:  and  this  because  the  being  of  the 
form  is  the  same  as  that  of  its  matter,  and  this  is  the  being 
of  the  composite.  Now  the  soul  subsists  in  its  own  being, 
as  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  LXXV.,  A.  2).  It  follows, 
therefore,  that  after  being  separated  from  the  body  it  has 
perfect  being,  and  that  consequently  it  can  have  a  perfect 
operation;  although  it  has  not  the  perfect  specific  nature. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Happiness  belongs  to  man  in  respect  of  his 
intellect:  and,  therefore,  since  the  intellect  remains,  it  can 
have  Happiness.  Thus  the  teeth  of  an  Ethiopian,  in  respect 
of  which  he  is  said  to  be  white,  can  retain  their  whiteness, 
even  after  extraction. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  One  thing  is  hindered  by  another  in  two 
ways.  First,  by  way  of  opposition;  thus  cold  hinders  the 
action  of  heat:  and  such  a  hindrance  to  operation  is 
repugnant  to  Happiness.  Secondly,  by  way  of  some  kind 
of  defect,  because,  to  wit,  that  which  is  hindered  has  not  all 
that  is  necessary  to  make  it  perfect  in  every  way :  and  such 
a  hindrance  to  operation  is  not  incompatible  with  Happiness, 
but  prevents  it  from  being  perfect  in  every  way.  And  thus 
it  is  that  separation  from  the  body  is  said  to  hold  the  soul 
back  from  tending  with  all  its  might  to  the  vision  of  the 
Divine  Essence.  For  the  soul  desires  to  see  God  in  such  a 
way  that  the  enjoyment  also  may  overflow  into  the  body, 
as  far  as  possible.  And  therefore,  as  long  as  it  enjoys  God, 
without  the  fellowship  of  the  body,  its  appetite  is  at  rest  in 
that  which  it  has,  in  such  a  way,  that  it  would  still  wish  the 
body  to  attain  to  its  share. 

Reply  Ohj.  5.  The  desire  of  the  separated  soul  is  entirely 
at  rest,  as  regards  the  thing  desired ;  since,  to  wit,  it  has  that 
which  suffices  its  appetite.  But  it  is  not  wholly  at  rest,  as 
regards  the  desirer,  since  it  does  not  possess  that  good  in 


WHAT  IS  REQUIRED  FOR  HAPPINESS  63 

every  way  that  it  would  wish  to  possess  it.  Consequently, 
after  the  body  has  been  resumed,  Happiness  increases  not  in 
intensity,  but  in  extent. 

Reply  Ohj.  6.  The  passage  quoted  to  the  effect  that  the 
souls  of  the  departed  see  not  God  as  the  angels  do,  is  not  to  be 
understood  as  referring  to  inequality  of  quantity;  because 
even  now  some  souls  of  the  Blessed  are  raised  to  the  higher 
orders  of  angels,  thus  seeing  God  more  clearly  than  the 
lower  angels.  But  it  refers  to  inequality  of  proportion: 
because  the  angels,  even  the  lowest,  have  every  perfection 
of  Happiness  that  they  ever  will  have,  whereas  the  separated 
souls  of  the  saints  have  not. 


Sixth  Article. 

whether  perfection  of  the  body  is  necessary 
for  happiness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  perfection  of  the  body  is  not 
necessary  for  man's  perfect  Happiness.  For  perfection  of 
the  body  is  a  bodily  good.  But  it  has  been  shown  above 
(Q.  II.)  that  Happiness  does  not  consist  in  bodily  goods. 
Therefore  no  perfect  disposition  of  the  body  is  necessary  for 
man's  Happiness. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  man's  Happiness  consists  in  the  vision 
of  the  Divine  Essence,  as  shown  above  (Q.  III.,  A.  8).  But 
the  body  has  no  part  in  this  operation,  as  shown  above 
(A.  5).  Therefore  no  disposition  of  the  body  is  necessary 
for  Happiness. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  more  the  intellect  is  abstracted  from 
the  body,  the  more  perfectly  it  understands.  But  Happiness 
consists  in  the  most  perfect  operation  of  the  intellect. 
Therefore  the  soul  should  be  abstracted  from  the  body  in 
every  way.  Therefore,  in  no  way  is  a  disposition  of  the  body 
necessary  for  Happiness. 

On  the  contrary,  Happiness  is  the  reward  of  virtue;  where- 
fore it  is  written  (John  xiii.  17) :  You  shall  he  hlessed,  if  you 
do  them.     But  the  reward  promised  to  the  saints,  is  not  only 


/; 


'h  question  IV 

that  they  shall  see  and  enjoy  God,  but  also  that  their  bodies 
shall  be  well-disposed ;  for  it  is  written  (Isa.  Ixvi.  14) :  You 
shall  see  and  your  heart  shall  rejoice,  and  your  bones  shall 
flourish  like  a  herb.  Therefore  good  disposition  of  the  body 
is  necessary  for  Happiness. 

/  answer  that,  If  we  speak  of  that  happiness  which  man 
can  acquire  in  this  life,  it  is  evident  that  a  well-disposed 
body  is  of  necessity  required  for  it.  For  this  happiness 
consists,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  i.)  in  an 
operation  according  to  perfect  virtue  ;  and  it  is  clear  that  man 
can  be  hindered,  by  indisposition  of  the  body,  from  every 
operation  of  virtue. 

But  speaking  of  perfect  Happiness,  some  have  maintained 
that  no  disposition  of  body  is  necessary  for  Happiness; 
indeed,  that  it  is  necessary  for  the  soul  to  be  entirely  sepa- 
rated from  the  body.  Hence  Augustine  {De  Civ.  Dei.  xxvi.) 
quotes  the  words  of  Porphyry  who  said  that  for  the  soul  to  be 
happy,  it  must  he  severed  from  everything  corporeal.  But  this 
is  unreasonable.  For  since  it  is  natural  to  the  soul  to  be 
united  to  the  body;  it  is  not  possible  for  the  perfection  of 
the  soul  to  exclude  its  natural  perfection. 

Consequently,  we  must  say  that  perfect  disposition  of  the 
body  is  necessary,  both  antecedently  and  consequently,  for 
that  Happiness  which  is  in  all  ways  perfect. — ^Antecedently, 
because,  as  Augustine  says  [Gen.  ad  lit.  xii.),  if  the  body  be 
such,  that  the  governance  thereof  is  difficult  (ind  burdensome, 
like  unto  flesh  which  is  corruptible  and  weighs  upon  the  soul, 
the  mind  is  turned  away  from  that  vision  of  the  highest  heaven. 
Whence  he  concludes  that,  when  this  body  will  no  longer  be 
*  natural,  *  but  '  spiritual, '  then  will  it  be  equalled  to  the 
angels,  and  that  will  be  its  glory,  which  erstwhile  was  its  burden. 
— Consequently,  because  from  the  Happiness  of  the  soul 
there  will  be  an  overflow  on  to  the  body,  so  that  this  too  will 
obtain  its  perfection.  Hence  Augustine  says  (Ep.  ad 
Dioscor.)  that  God  gave  the  soul  such  a  powerful  nature  that 
from  its  exceeding  fulness  of  happiness  the  vigour  of  incor- 
ruption  overflows  into  the  lower  nature. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Happiness  does  not  consist  in  bodily  good  as 


WHAT  IS  REQUIRED  FOR  HAPPINESS  65 

its  object:  but  bodily  good  can  add  a  certain  charm  and 
perfection  to  Happiness. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  the  body  has  no  part  in  that 
operation  of  the  intellect  whereby  the  Essence  of  God  is 
seen,  yet  it  might  prove  a  hindrance  thereto.  Consequently, 
perfection  of  the  body  is  necessary,  lest  it  hinder  the  mind 
from  being  lifted  up. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  perfect  operation  of  the  intellect  re- 
quires indeed  that  the  intellect  be  abstracted  from  this 
corruptible  body  which  weighs  upon  the  soul;  but  not  from 
the  spiritual  body,  which  will  be  wholly  subject  to  the 
spirit.  On  this  point  we  shall  treat  in  the  Third  Part  of  this 
work  (SuppL,  Q.  LXXXIL). 

Seventh  Article. 

whether  any  external  goods  are  necessary 
for  happiness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  A  Hide  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  external  goods  also  are  neces- 
sary for  Happiness.  For  that  which  is  promised  the  saints 
for  reward,  belongs  to  Happiness.  But  external  goods  are 
promised  the  saints;  for  instance,  food  and  drink,  wealth, 
and  a  kingdom:  for  it  is  said  (Luke  xxii.,  30) :  That  you  may 
eat  and  drink  at  My  tahlein  My  kingdom :  and  (Matth.  vi.  20) : 
Lay  up  to  yourselves  treasures  in  heaven  :  and  (Matth.  xxv.  34) : 
Come,  ye  blessed  of  my  Father,  possess  you  the  kingdom. 
Therefore  external  goods  are  necessary  for  Happiness. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  according  to  Boethius  {De  Consol.  iii.), 
happiness  is  a  state  made  perfect  by  the  aggregate  of  all  good 
things.  But  some  of  man's  goods  are  external,  although 
they  be  of  least  account,  as  Augustine  says  {De  Lib.  Arb.  ii.). 
Therefore  they  too  are  necessary  for  Happiness. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Our  Lord  said  (Matth.  v.  12) :  Your  reward 
is  very  great  in  heaven.  But  to  be  in  heaven  implies  being  in 
a  place.  Therefore  at  least  external  place  is  necessary  for 
Happiness. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  (Ps.  Ixxii.  25) :  For  what  have 

II.  I  5 


66  QUESTION  IV 

/  in  heaven  ?  and  besides  Thee  what  do  I  desire  upon  earth  ? 
As  though  to  say:  '  I  desh*e  nothing  but  this/ — It  is  good 
for  me  to  adhere  to  my  God.  Therefore  nothing  further 
external  is  necessary  for  Happiness. 

/  answer  that,  For  imperfect  happiness,  such  as  can  be  had 
in  this  hfe,  external  goods  are  necessary,  not  as  belonging 
to  the  essence  of  happiness,  but  by  serving  as  instruments 
to  happiness,  which  consists  in  an  operation  of  virtue,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  i.  For  man  needs,  in  this  life,  the  neces- 
saries of  the  body,  both  for  the  operation  of  contemplative 
virtue,  and  for  the  operation  of  active  virtue,  for  which 
latter  he  needs  also  many  other  things  by  means  of  which 
to  perform  its  operations. 

On  the  other  hand,  such  goods  as  these  are  nowise  neces- 
sary for  perfect  Happiness,  which  consists  in  seeing  God. 
The  reason  of  this  is  that  all  suchlike  external  goods  are 
requisite  either  for  the  support  of  the  animal  body;  or  for 
certain  operations  which  belong  to  human  life,  which  we 
perform  by  means  of  the  animal  body :  whereas  that  perfect 
Happiness  which  consists  in  seeing  God,  will  be  either  in 
the  soul  separated  from  the  body,  or  in  the  soul  united  to 
the  body  then  no  longer  animal  but  spiritual.  Consequently 
these  external  goods  are  nowise  necessary  for  that  Happi- 
ness, since  they  are  ordained  to  the  animal  life. — And  since, 
in  this  life,  the  felicity  of  contemplation,  as  being  more 
God-like,  approaches  nearer  than  that  of  action  to  the  like- 
ness of  that  perfect  Happiness,  therefore  it  stands  in  less 
need  of  these  goods  of  the  body,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  x. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  All  those  material  promises  contained  in 
Holy  Scripture,  are  to  be  understood  metaphorically,  inas- 
much as  Scripture  is  wont  to  express  spiritual  things  under 
the  form  of  things  corporeal,  in  order  that  from  things  we 
know,  we  may  rise  to  the  desire  of  things  unknown,  as  Gregory 
says  in  a  homily  (xi.  in  Evang.).  Thus  food  and  drink 
signify  the  delight  of  Happiness:  wealth,  the  sufficiency  of 
God  for  man;  the  kingdom,  the  lifting  up  of  man  to  union 
with  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  These  goods  that  serve  for  the  animal  life, 


WHAT  IS  REQUIRED  FOR  HAPPINESS  67 

are  incompatible  with  that  spiritual  life  wherein  perfect 
Happiness  consists.  Nevertheless  in  that  Happiness  there 
will  be  the  aggregate  of  all  good  things,  because  whatever 
good  there  be  in  these  things,  we  shall  possess  it  all  in  the 
Supreme  Fount  of  goodness. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  According  to  Augustine  (De  Serm.  Dom. 
in  Monte  i.),  it  is  not  a  material  heaven  that  is  described  as 
the  reward  of  the  saints,  but  a  heaven  raised  on  the  height 
of  spiritual  goods.  Nevertheless  a  bodily  place,  viz.,  the 
empyrean  heaven,  will  be  appointed  to  the  Blessed,  not  as  a 
need  of  Happiness,  but  by  reason  of  a  certain  fitness  and 
adornment. 

Eighth  Article. 

whether  the  fellowship  of  friends  is  necessary  for 

happiness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  friends  are  necessary  for  Happi- 
ness. For  future  Happiness  is  frequently  designated  by 
Scripture  under  the  name  of  glory.  But  glory  consists  in 
man's  good  being  brought  to  the  notice  of  many.  There- 
fore the  fellowship  of  friends  is  necessary  for  Happiness. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Boethius  says  that  there  is  no  delight  in 
possessing  any  good  whatever,  without  someone  to  share  it  with 
us.  But  delight  is  necessary  for  Happiness.  Therefore 
fellowship  of  friends  is  also  necessary. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  charity  is  perfected  in  Happiness.  But 
charity  includes  the  love  of  God  and  of  our  neighbour. 
Therefore  it  seems  that  fellowship  of  friends  is  necessary 
for  Happiness. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Wisd.  vii.  11) :  All  good  things 
came  to  me  together  with  her,  i.e.,  with  wisdom,  which  consists 
in  contemplating  God.  Consequently  nothing  else  is  neces- 
sary for  Happiness. 

/  answer  that,  If  we  speak  of  the  happiness  of  this  life, 
the  happy  man  needs  friends,  as  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic,  ix.),  not,  indeed,  to  make  use  of  them,  since  he  suf- 
fices himself;   nor  to  delight  in  them,   since  he  possesses 


68  QUESTION  IV 

perfect  delight  in  the  operation  of  virtue;  but  for  the  pur- 
pose of  a  good  operation,  viz.,  that  he  may  do  good  to  them; 
that  he  may  dehght  in  seeing  them  do  good ;  and  again  that 
he  may  be  helped  by  them  in  his  good  work.  For  in  order 
that  man  may  do  well,  whether  in  the  works  of  the  active  life, 
or  in  those  of  the  contemplative  life,  he  needs  the  fellowship 
of  friends. 

But  if  we  speak  of  perfect  Happiness  which  will  be  in 
our  heavenly  Fatherland,  the  fellowship  of  friends  is  not 
essential  to  Happiness;  since  man  has  the  entire  fulness  of 
his  perfection  in  God.  But  the  fellowship  of  friends  con- 
duces to  the  well-being  of  Happiness.  Hence  Augustine 
says  (Gen.  ad  lit.  viii.)  that  the  spiritual  creatures  receive  no 
other  interior  aid  to  happiness  than  the  eternity,  truth,  and 
charity  of  the  Creator.  But  if  they  can  he  said  to  he  helped 
from  without,  perhaps  it  is  only  hy  this  that  they  see  one 
another  and  rejoice  in  God,  at  their  fellowship. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  That  glory  which  is  essential  to  Happiness, 
is  that  which  man  has,  not  with  man  but  with  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  This  saying  is  to  be  understood  of  the  pos- 
session of  good  that  does  not  fully  satisfy.  This  does  not 
apply  to  the  question  under  consideration;  because  man 
possesses  in  God  a  sufficiency  of  every  good. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Perfection  of  charity  is  essential  to  Happi- 
ness, as  to  the  love  of  God,  but  not  as  to  the  love  of  our 
neighbour.  Wherefore  if  there  were  but  one  soul  enjoying 
God,  it  would  be  happy,  though  having  no  neighbour  to 
love.  But  supposing  one  neighbour  to  be  there,  love  of 
him  results  from  perfect  love  of  God.  Consequently,  friend- 
ship is,  as  it  were,  concomitant  with  perfect  Happiness. 


QUESTION  V. 

OF  THE  ATTAINMENT  OF  HAPPINESS. 

{In  Eight  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  attainment  of  Happiness.  Under 
this  heading  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether 
man  can  attain  Happiness  ?  (2)  Whether  one  man  can 
be  happier  than  another  ?  (3)  Whether  any  man  can  be 
happy  in  this  Hfe  ?  (4)  Whether  Happiness  once  had  can 
be  lost  ?  (5)  Whether  man  can  attain  Happiness  by  means 
of  his  natural  powers  ?  (6)  Whether  man  attains  Happi- 
ness through  the  action  of  some  higher  creature  ? 
(7)  Whether  any  actions  of  man  are  necessary  in  order  that 
man  may  obtain  Happiness  of  God  ?  (8)  Whether  every 
man  desires  Happiness  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  man  can  attain  happiness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man  cannot  attain  happiness. 
For  just  as  the  rational  is  above  the  sensible  nature,  so  the 
intellectual  is  above  the  rational,  as  Dionysius  declares 
{Div.  Nom.  iv.,  vi.,  vii.)  in  several  passages.  But  irrational 
animals  that  have  the  sensitive  nature  only,  cannot  attain 
the  end  of  the  rational  nature.  Therefore  neither  can  man, 
who  is  of  rational  nature,  attain  the  end  of  the  intellectual 
creature,  which  is  Happiness. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  True  Happiness  consists  in  seeing  God, 
Who  is  pure  Truth.  But  from  his  very  nature,  man  con- 
siders truth  in  material  things:   wherefore  he  understands 

69 


70  QUESTION  V 

the  intelligible  species  in  the  phantasm  (De  Anima  iii.). 
Therefore  he  cannot  attain  Happiness. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Happiness  consists  in  attaining  the  Sove- 
reign Good.  But  we  cannot  arrive  at  the  top  without  sur- 
mounting the  middle.  Since,  therefore,  the  angeHc  nature 
through  which  man  cannot  mount  is  midway  between  God 
and  human  nature;  it  seems  that  he  cannot  attain  Happiness. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  xciii.  12) :  Blessed  is  the 
man  whom  Thou  shall  instruct,  0  Lord. 

I  answer  that,  Happiness  is  the  attainment  of  the  Perfect 
Good.  Whoever,  therefore,  is  capable  of  the  Perfect  Good 
can  attain  Happiness.  Now,  that  man  is  capable  of  the 
Perfect  Good,  is  proved  both  because  his  intellect  can  appre- 
hend the  universal  and  perfect  good,  and  because  his  will 
can  desire  it.  And  therefore  man  can  attain  Happiness. — 
This  can  be  proved  again  from  the  fact  that  man  is  capable 
of  seeing  God,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XII.,  A.  i) : 
in  which  vision,  as  we  stated  above  (Q.  III.,  A.  8)  man's 
perfect  Happiness  consists. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  rational  exceeds  the  sensitive  nature, 
otherwise  than  the  intellectual  surpasses  the  rational.  For 
the  rational  exceeds  the  sensitive  nature  in  respect  of  the 
object  of  its  knowledge:  since  the  senses  have  no  knowledge 
whatever  of  the  universal,  whereas  the  reason  has  know- 
ledge thereof.  But  the  intellectual  surpasses  the  rational 
nature,  as  to  the  mode  of  knowing  the  same  intelligible 
truth :  for  the  intellectual  nature  grasps  forthwith  the  truth 
which  the  rational  nature  reaches  by  the  inquiry  of  reason, 
as  was  made  clear  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  LVIL,  A.  3; 
Q.  LXXIX.,  A.  8).  Therefore  reason  arrives  by  a  kind  of 
movement  at  that  which  the  intellect  grasps.  Consequently 
the  rational  nature  can  attain  Happiness,  which  is  the  per- 
fection of  the  intellectual  nature:  but  otherwise  than  the 
angels.  Because  the  angels  attained  it  forthwith  after  the 
beginning  of  their  creation:  whereas  man  attains  it  after  a 
time.     But  the  sensitive  nature  can  nowise  attain  this  end. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  To  man  in  the  present  state  of  life  the 
natural  way  of  knowing  intelligible  truth  is  by  means  of 


THE  ATTAINMENT  OF  HAPPINESS  71 

phantasms.  But  after  this  state  of  hfe,  he  has  another 
natural  way,  as  was  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  LXXXIV., 
A.  7;  Q.  LXXXIX.,  A.  7). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Man  cannot  surmount  the  angels  in  the 
degree  of  nature,  so  as  to  be  above  them  naturally.  But 
he  can  surmount  them  by  an  operation  of  the  intellect,  by 
understanding  that  there  is  above  the  angels  something 
that  makes  men  happy;  and  that  when  he  has  attained  it, 
he  will  be  perfectly  happy. 

Second  Article, 
whether  one  man  can  be  happier  than  another  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  one  man  cannot  be  happier 
than  another.  For  Happiness  is  the  reward  of  virtue,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  i.).  But  equal  reward  is  given  for 
all  the  works  of  virtue;  because  it  is  written  (Matth.  xx.  10) 
that  all  who  laboured  in  the  vineyard  received  every  man  a 
penny ;  for,  as  Gregory  says  [Horn.  xix.  in  Evang),  each 
was  equally  rewarded  with  eternal  life.  Therefore  one  man 
cannot  be  happier  than  another. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Happiness  is  the  supreme  good.  But 
nothing  can  surpass  the  supreme.  Therefore  one  man's 
Happiness  cannot  be  surpassed  by  another's. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  since  Happiness  is  the  perfect  and  sufficient 
good  {Ethic,  i.)  it  brings  rest  to  man's  desire.  But  his  desire 
is  not  at  rest,  if  he  yet  lacks  some  good  that  can  be  got. 
And  if  he  lack  nothing  that  he  can  get,  there  can  be  no  still 
greater  good.  Therefore  either  man  is  not  happy;  or,  if  he 
be  happy,  no  other  Happiness  can  be  greater. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (John  xiv.  2) :  In  My  Father's 
house  there  are  many  mansions ;  which,  according  to 
Augustine  {Tract.  Ixvii.)  signify  the  diverse  dignities  of 
merits  in  the  one  eternal  life.  But  the  dignity  of  eternal  life 
which  is  given  according  to  merit,  is  Happiness  itself. 
Therefore  there  are  diverse  degrees  of  Happiness,  and  Happi- 
ness is  not  equally  in  all. 


72      .  QUESTION  V 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  8;  Q.  II.,  A.  7), 
Happiness  implies  two  things,  to  wit,  the  last  end  itself, 
i.e.,  the  Sovereign  Good;  and  the  attainment  or  enjoyment 
of  that  same  Good.  As  to  that  Good  itself,  Which  is  the 
object  and  cause  of  Happiness,  one  Happiness  cannot  be 
greater  than  another,  since  there  is  but  one  Sovereign  Good, 
namely,  God,  by  enjoying  Whom,  men  are  made  happy. — 
But  as  to  the  attainment  or  enjoyment  of  this  Good,  one 
man  can  be  happier  than  another ;  because  the  more  a  man 
enjoys  this  Good  the  happier  he  is.  Now,  that  one  man 
enjoys  God  more  than  another,  happens  through  his  being 
better  disposed  or  ordered  to  the  enjoyment  of  Him.  And 
in  this  sense  one  man  can  be  happier  than  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  one  penny  signifies  that  Happiness  is  one 
in  its  object.  But  the  many  mansions  signify  the  manifold 
Happiness  in  the  divers  degrees  of  enjoyment. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Happiness  is  said  to  be  the  supreme  good, 
inasmuch  as  it  is  the  perfect  possession  or  enjoyment  of  the 
Supreme  Good. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  None  of  the  Blessed  lacks  any  desirable 
good ;  since  they  have  the  Infinite  Good  Itself,  Which  is  the 
good  of  all  good,  as  Augustine  says  (Enarr.  in  Ps.  cxxxiv.). 
But  one  is  said  to  be  happier  than  another,  by  reason  of 
diverse  participation  of  the  same  good.  And  the  addition 
of  other  goods  does  not  increase  Happiness,  hence  Augustine 
says  (Conf.  v.) :  He  who  knows  Thee,  and  others  hesides,  is  not 
the  happier  for  knowing  them,  hut  is  happy  for  knowing  Thee 
alone. 

Third  Article, 
whether  one  can  be  happy  in  this  life  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  Happiness  can  be  had  in  this 
life.  For  it  is  written  (Ps.  cxviii.  i) :  Blessed  are  the  unde- 
filed  in  the  way,  who  walk  in  the  law  of  the  Lord.  But  this 
happens  in  this  life.     Therefore  one  can  be  happy  in  this  life. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  imperfect  participation  in  the  Sovereign 
Good  does  not  destroy  the  nature  of  Happiness,  otherwise 


THE  ATTAINMENT  OF  HAPPINESS  73 

one  would  not  be  happier  than  another.  But  men  can 
participate  in  the  Sovereign  Good  in  this  life,  by  knowing 
and  loving  God,  albeit  imperfectly.  Therefore  man  can  be 
happy  in  this  life. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  what  is  said  by  many  cannot  be  alto- 
gether false :  since  what  is  in  many,  comes,  apparently,  from 
nature;  and  nature  does  not  fail  altogether.  Now  many  say 
that  Happiness  can  be  had  in  this  life,  as  appears  from 
Ps.  cxliii.  15:  They  have  called  the  people  happy  that  hath 
these  things,  to  wit,  the  good  things  of  this  life.  Therefore 
one  can  be  happy  in  this  life. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Job  xiv.  i) :  Man  horn  of  a 
woman,  living  for  a  short  time,  is  filled  with  many  miseries. 
But  Happiness  excludes  misery.  Therefore  man  cannot  be 
happy  in  this  life. 

I  answer  that,  A  certain  participation  of  Happiness  can  be 
had  in  this  life:  but  perfect  and  true  Happiness  cannot  be 
had  in  this  life.  This  may  be  seen  from  a  twofold  con- 
sideration. 

First,  from  the  general  notion  of  happiness.  For  since 
happiness  is  a  perfect  and  sufficient  good,  it  excludes  every 
evil,  and  fulfils  every  desire.  But  in  this  life  every  evil 
cannot  be  excluded.  For  this  present  life  is  subject  to  many 
unavoidable  evils;  to  ignorance  on  the  part  of  the  intellect; 
to  inordinate  affection  on  the  part  of  the  appetite,  and  to 
many  penalties  on  the  part  of  the  body;  as  Augustine  sets 
forth  in  De  Civ.  Dei.  chap.  iv.  Likewise  neither  can  the 
desire  for  good  be  satiated  in  this  life.  For  man  naturally 
desires  the  good,  which  he  has,  to  be  abiding.  Now  the 
goods  of  the  present  life  pass  away;  since  life  itself  passes 
away,  which  we  naturally  desire  to  have,  and  would  wish  to 
hold  abidingly,  for  man  naturally  shrinks  from  death. 
Wherefore  it  is  impossible  to  have  true  Happiness  in  this  life. 

Secondly,  from  a  consideration  of  the  specific  nature  of 
Happiness,  viz.,  the  vision  of  the  Divine  Essence,  which 
man  cannot  obtain  in  this  life,  as  was  shown  in  the  First 
Part  (Q.  XII.,  A.  2).  Hence  it  is  evident  that  none  can 
attain  true  and  perfect  Happiness  in  this  life. 


74  QUESTION  V 

Reply  Ohj,  i.  Some  are  said  to  be  happy  in  this  life,  either 
on  account  of  the  hope  of  obtaining  Happiness  in  the  Hfe 
to  come,  according  to  Rom.  viii.  24:  We  are  saved  by  hope  ; 
or  on  account  of  a  certain  participation  of  Happiness,  by 
reason  of  a  kind  of  enjoyment  of  the  Sovereign  Good. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  imperfection  of  participated  Happiness 
is  due  to  one  of  two  causes.  First,  on  the  part  of  the  object 
of  Happiness,  which  is  not  seen  in  Its  Essence:  and  this 
imperfection  destroys  the  nature  of  true  Happiness. 
Secondly,  the  imperfection  may  be  on  the  part  of  the  par- 
ticipator, who  indeed  attains  the  object  of  Happiness,  in 
itself,  namely,  God;  imperfectly,  however,  in  comparison 
with  the  way  in  which  God  enjoys  Himself.  This  imper- 
fection does  not  destroy  the  true  nature  of  Happiness; 
because,  since  Happiness  is  an  operation,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  III.,  A.  2),  the  true  nature  of  Happiness  is  taken  from 
the  object,  which  specifies  the  act,  and  not  from  the 
subject. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Men  esteem  that  there  is  some  kind  of 
happiness  to  be  had  in  this  life,  on  account  of  a  certain 
likeness  to  true  Happiness.  And  thus  they  do  not  fail 
altogether  in  their  estimate. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  happiness  once  had  can  be  lost  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  Happiness  can  be  lost.  For 
Happiness  is  a  perfection.  But  every  perfection  is  in  the 
thing  perfected  according  to  the  mode  of  the  latter.  Since 
then  man  is,  by  his  nature,  changeable,  it  seems  that  Happi- 
ness is  participated  by  man  in  a  changeable  manner.  And 
consequently  it  seems  that  man  can  lose  Happiness. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Happiness  consists  in  an  act  of  the 
intellect;  and  the  intellect  is  subject  to  the  will.  But  the 
will  can  be  directed  to  opposites.  Therefore  it  seems  that 
it  can  desist  from  the  operation  whereby  man  is  made 
happy:  and  thus  man  will  cease  to  be  happy. 


THE  ATTAINMENT  OF  HAPPINESS  75 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  end  corresponds  to  the  beginning. 
But  man's  Happiness  has  a  beginning,  since  man  was  not 
always  happy.     Therefore  it  seems  that  it  has  an  end. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Matth.  xxv.  46)  of  the 
righteous  that  they  shall  go  .  .  .  into  life  everlasting,  which, 
as  above  stated  (A.  2),  is  the  Happiness  of  the  saints.  Now 
what  is  eternal  ceases  not.  Therefore  Happiness  cannot 
be  lost. 

/  answer  that.  If  we  speak  of  imperfect  happiness,  such  as 
can  be  had  in  this  life,  in  this  sense  it  can  be  lost.  This  is 
clear  of  contemplative  happiness,  which  is  lost  either  by 
forgetfulness,  for  instance,  when  knowledge  is  lost  through 
sickness;  or  again  by  certain  occupations,  whereby  a  man 
is  altogether  withdrawn  from  contemplation. 

This  is  also  clear  of  active  happiness :  since  man's  will  can 
be  changed  so  as  to  fall  to  vice  from  the  virtue,  in  whose  act 
that  happiness  principally  consists.  If,  however,  the  virtue 
remain  unimpaired,  outward  changes  can  indeed  disturb 
suchlike  happiness,  in  so  far  as  they  hinder  many  acts  of 
virtue;  but  they  cannot  take  it  away  altogether,  because 
there  still  remains  an  act  of  virtue,  whereby  man  bears  these 
trials  in  a  praiseworthy  manner. — -And  since  the  happiness 
of  this  life  can  be  lost,  a  circumstance  that  appears  to  be 
contrary  to  the  nature  of  happiness,  therefore  did  the 
Philosopher  state  (Ethic,  i.)  that  some  are  happy  in  this 
life,  not  simply,  but  as  men,  whose  nature  is  subject  to 
change. 

But  if  we  speak  of  that  perfect  Happiness  which  we 
await  after  this  life,  it  must  be  observed  that  Origen  (Peri 
Archon,  ii.),  following  the  error  of  certain  Platonists,  held 
that  man  can  become  unhappy  after  the  final  Happiness. 

This,  however,  is  evidently  false,  for  two  reasons.  First, 
from  the  general  notion  of  happiness.  For  since  happiness  is 
the  perfect  and  sufficient  good,  it  must  needs  set  man's  desire 
at  rest  and  exclude  every  evil.  Now  man  naturally  desires 
to  hold  to  the  good  that  he  has,  and  to  have  the  surety  of  his 
holding :  else  he  must  of  necessity  be  troubled  with  the  fear 
of  losing  it,  or  with  the  sorrow  of  knowing  that  he  will  lose  it. 


76  QUESTION  V 

Therefore  it  is  necessary  for  true  Happiness  that  man  have 
the  assured  opinion  of  never  losing  the  good  that  he  possesses. 
If  this  opinion  be  true,  it  follows  that  he  never  will  lose  hap- 
piness: but  if  it  be  false,  it  is  in  itself  an  evil  that  he  should 
have  a  false  opinion:  because  the  false  is  the  evil  of  the 
intellect,  just  as  the  true  is  its  good,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  vi. 
Consequently  he  will  no  longer  be  truly  happy,  if  evil  be  in 
him. 

Secondly,  it  is  again  evident  if  we  consider  the  specific 
nature  of  Happiness.     For  it  has  been  shown  above  (Q.  III., 
A.  8)  that  man's  perfect  Happiness  consists  in  the  vision  of 
the  Divine  Essence.     Now  it  is  impossible  for  anyone  seeing 
the  Divine  Essence,  to  wish  not  to  see  It.     Because  every 
good  that  one  possesses  and  yet  wishes  to  be  without,  is 
either  insufficient,  something  more  sufficing  being  desired 
in  its  stead;  or  else  has  some  inconvenience  attached  to  it, 
by  reason  of  which  it  becomes  wearisome.     But  the  vision 
of  the  Divine  Essence  fills  the  soul  with  all  good  things,  since 
it  unites  it  to  the  source  of  all  goodness;  hence  it  is  written 
(Ps.  xvi.  15) :  /  shall  he  satisfied  when  Thy  glory  shall  appear  ; 
and  (Wis.  vii.  11):  All  good  things  came  to  me  together  with 
her,  i.e.,  with  the  contemplation  of  wisdom.     In  like  manner 
neither  has  it  any  inconvenience  attached  to  it;  because  it  is 
written  of  the  contemplation  of  wisdom   (Wis.   viii.   16) : 
Her  conversation  hath  no  bitterness,   nor  her  company  any 
tediousness.     It  is  thus  evident  that  the  happy  man  cannot 
forsake  Happiness  of  his  own  accord. — -Moreover,  neither  can 
he  lose  Happiness,  through  God  taking  it  away  from  him. 
Because,  since  the  withdrawal  of  Happiness  is  a  punishment, 
it  cannot  be  enforced  by  God,  the  just  Judge,  except  for 
some  fault ;  and  he  that  sees  God  cannot  fall  into  a  fault,  since 
rectitude  of  the  will,  of  necessity,  results  from  that  vision 
as  was  shown  above  (Q.  IV.,  A.  4). — Nor  again  can  it  be 
withdrawn  by  any  other  agent.     Because  the  mind  that  is 
united  to  God  is  raised  above  all  other  things:  and  conse- 
quently no  other  agent  can  sever  the  mind  from  that  union. 
Therefore  it  seems  unreasonable  that  as  time  goes  on,  man 
should  pass  from  happiness  to  misery,  and  vice  versa  ;  because 


THE  lATTAINMENT  OF  HAPPINESS  ^^ 

suchlike  vicissitudes  of  time  can  only  be  for  such  things  as 
are  subject  to  time  and  movement. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Happiness  is  consummate  perfection,  which 
excludes  every  defect  from  the  happy.  And  therefore  who- 
ever has  happiness  has  it  altogether  unchangeably :  this  is 
done  by  the  Divine  power,  which  raises  man  to  the  partici- 
pation of  eternity  which  transcends  all  change. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  will  can  be  directed  to  opposites,  in 
things  which  are  ordained  to  the  end ;  but  it  is  ordained,  of 
natural  necessity,  to  the  last  end.  This  is  evident  from  the 
fact  that  man  is  unable  not  to  wish  to  be  happy. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Happiness  has  a  beginning  owing  to  the 
condition  of  the  participator:  but  it  has  no  end  by  reason 
of  the  condition  of  the  good,  the  participation  of  which 
makes  man  happy.  Hence  the  beginning  of  happiness  is 
from  one  cause,  its  endlessness  is  from  another. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  man  can  attain  happiness  by  his  natural 

POWERS  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man  can  attain  Happiness  by  his 
natural  powers.  For  nature  does  not  fail  in  necessary  things. 
But  nothing  is  so  natural  to  man  than  that  by  which  he 
attains  the  last  end.  Therefore  this  is  not  lacking  to  human 
nature.  Therefore  man  can  attain  Happiness  by  his  natural 
powers. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  since  man  is  more  noble  than  irrational 
creatures,  it  seems  that  he  must  be  better  equipped  than 
they.  But  irrational  creatures  can  attain  their  end  by  their 
natural  powers.  Much  more  therefore  can  man  attain 
Happiness  by  his  natural  powers. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Happiness  is  a  perfect  operation,  according 
to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  vii.).  Now  the  beginning  of  a 
thing  belongs  to  the  same  principle  as  the  perfecting  thereof. 
Since,  therefore,  the  imperfect  operation,  which  is  as  the 
beginning  in  human  operations,  is  subject  to  man's  natural 


7^  QUESTION  V 

power,  whereby  he  is  master  of  his  own  actions ;  it  seems  that 
he  can  attain  to  perfect  operation,  i.e.,  Happiness,  by  his 
natural  powers. 

On  the  contrary,  Man  is  naturally  the  principle  of  his 
action,  by  his  intellect  and  will.  But  final  Happiness  pre- 
pared for  the  saints,  surpasses  the  intellect  and  will  of  man ; 
for  the  Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  ii.  9) :  Eye  hath  not  seen,  nor  ear 
heard,  neither  hath  it  entered  into  the  heart  of  man,  what  things 
God  hath  prepared  for  them  that  love  Him.  Therefore  man 
cannot  attain  Happiness  by  his  natural  powers. 

I  answer  that,  Imperfect  happiness  that  can  be  had  in  this 
life,  can  be  acquired  by  man  by  his  natural  powers,  in  the 
same  way  as  virtue,  in  whose  operation  it  consists:  on  this 
point  we  shall  speak  further  on  (Q.  LXIIL).  But  man's 
perfect  Happiness,  as  stated  above  (Q.  III.,  A.  8),  consists  in 
the  vision  of  the  Divine  Essence.  Now  the  vision  of  God's 
Essence  surpasses  the  nature  not  only  of  man,  but  also  of 
every  creature,  as  was  shown  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XII., 
A.  4).  For  the  natural  knowledge  of  every  creature  is  in 
keeping  with  the  mode  of  its  substance:  thus  it  is  said  of  the 
intelligence  (De  Causis  ;  Prop,  viii.)  that  it  knows  things  that 
are  above  it,  and  things  that  are  below  it,  according  to  the  mode 
of  its  substance.  But  every  knowledge  that  is  according  to 
the  mode  of  created  substance,  falls  short  of  the  vision  of 
the  Divine  Essence,  which  infinitely  surpasses  all  created 
substance.  Consequently  neither  man,  nor  any  creature, 
can  attain  final  Happiness  by  his  natural  powers. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Just  as  nature  does  not  fail  man  in  neces- 
saries, although  it  has  not  provided  him  with  weapons  and 
clothing,  as  it  provided  other  animals,  because  it  gave  him 
reason  and  hands,  with  which  he  is  able  to  get  these  things 
for  himself;  so  neither  did  it  fail  man  in  things  necessary, 
although  it  gave  him  not  the  wherewithal  to  attain  Happi- 
ness: since  this  it  could  not  do.  But  it  did  give  him  free- 
will, with  which  he  can  turn  to  God,  that  He  may  make  him 
happy.  For  what  we  do  by  means  of  our  friends,  is  done,  in 
a  sense,  by  ourselves  (Ethic,  iii.). 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  nature  that  can  attain  perfect  good, 


THE  ATTAINMENT  OF  HAPPINESS  79 

although  it  needs  help  from  without  in  order  to  attain  it,  is  of 
more  noble  condition  than  a  nature  which  cannot  attain 
perfect  good,  but  attains  some  imperfect  good,  although  it 
need  no  help  from  without  in  order  to  attain  it,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  {De  CcbIo  ii.).  Thus  he  is  better  disposed 
to  health  who  can  attain  perfect  health,  albeit  by  means  of 
medicine;  than  he  who  can  attain  but  imperfect  health, 
without  the  help  of  medicine.  And  therefore  the  rational 
creature,  which  can  attain  the  perfect  good  of  happiness, 
but  needs  the  Divine  assistance  for  the  purpose,  is  more 
perfect  than  the  irrational  creature,  which  is  not  capable  of 
attaining  this  good,  but  attains  some  imperfect  good  by  its 
natural  powers. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  When  imperfect  and  perfect  are  of  the  same 
species,  they  can  be  caused  by  the  same  power.  But  this 
does  not  follow  of  necessity,  if  they  be  of  different  species: 
for  not  everything,  that  can  cause  the  disposition  of  matter, 
can  produce  the  final  perfection.  Now  the  imperfect  opera- 
tion, which  is  subject  to  man's  natural  power,  is  not  of  the 
same  species  as  that  perfect  operation  which  is  man's  happi- 
ness: since  operation  takes  its  species  from  its  object. 
Consequently  the  argument  does  not  prove. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  man  attains  happiness  through  the  action 
of  some  higher  creature  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man  can  be  made  happy 
through  the  action  of  some  higher  creature,  viz.,  an  angel. 
For  since  we  observe  a  twofold  order  in  things — one,  of  the 
parts  of  the  universe  to  one  another,  the  other,  of  the  whole 
universe  to  a  good  which  is  outside  the  universe;  the  former 
order  is  ordained  to  the  second  as  to  its  end  (Metaph.  xii.). 
Thus  the  mutual  order  of  the  parts  of  an  army  is  dependent 
on  the  order  of  the  whole  army  to  the  general.  But  the 
mutual  order  of  the  parts  of  the  universe  consists  in  the 
higher  creatures  acting  on  the  lower,  as  stated  in  the  First 


8o  QUESTION  V 

Part  (Q.  CIX.,  A.  2) :  while  happiness  consists  in  the  order 
of  man  to  a  good  which  is  outside  the  universe,  i.e.,  God. 
Therefore  man  is  made  happy,  through  a  higher  creature, 
viz.,  an  angel,  acting  on  him. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  that  which  is  such  in  potentiality,  can 
be  reduced  to  act,  by  that  which  is  such  actually:  thus 
what  is  potentially  hot,  is  made  actually  hot,  by  something 
that  is  actually  hot.  But  man  is  potentially  happy.  There- 
fore he  can  be  made  actually  happy  by  an  angel  who  is 
actually  happy. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Happiness  consists  in  an  operation  of 
the  intellect,  as  stated  above  (Q.  IIL,  A.  4).  But  an  angel 
can  enlighten  man's  intellect,  as  shown  in  the  First  Part 
(Q.  CXI.,  A.  i).     Therefore  an  angel  can  make  a  man  happy. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  Ixxxiii.  12):  The  Lord 
will  give  grace  and  glory. 

I  answer  that,  Since  every  creature  is  subject  to  the  laws 
of  nature,  from  the  very  fact  that  its  power  and  action  are 
limited:  that  which  surpasses  created  nature,  cannot  be 
done  by  the  power  of  any  creature.  Consequently  if  any- 
thing need  to  be  done  that  is  above  nature,  it  is  done  by 
God  immediately;  such  as  raising  the  dead  to  life,  restoring 
sight  to  the  blind,  and  suchlike.  Now  it  has  been  shown 
above  (A.  5)  that  Happiness  is  a  good  surpassing  created 
nature.  Therefore  it  is  impossible  that  it  be  bestowed 
through  the  action  of  any  creature:  but  by  God  alone  is 
man  made  happy, — if  we  speak  of  perfect  Happiness.  If, 
however,  we  speak  of  imperfect  happiness,  the  same  is  to 
be  said  of  it  as  of  the  virtue,  in  whose  act  it  consists. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  It  often  happens  in  the  case  of  active  powers 
ordained  to  one  another,  that  it  belongs  to  the  highest 
power  to  reach  the  last  end,  while  the  lower  powers  con- 
tribute to  the  attainment  of  that  last  end,  by  causing  a 
disposition  thereto:  thus  to  the  art  of  sailing,  which  com- 
mands the  art  of  ship-building,  it  belongs  to  use  a  ship  for 
the  end  for  which  it  was  made.  Thus,  too,  in  the  order  of 
the  universe,  man  is  indeed  helped  by  angels  in  the  attain- 
ment of  his  last  end,  in  respect  of  certain  preliminary  dis- 


THE  ATTAINMENT  OF  HAPPINESS  8i 

positions  thereto:  whereas  he  attains  the  last  end  itself 
through  the  First  Agent,  which  is  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  When  a  form  exists  perfectly  and  naturally 
in  something,  it  can  be  the  principle  of  action  on  something 
else:  for  instance,  a  hot  thing  heats  through  fire.  But  if 
a  form  exist  in  something  imperfectly  and  not  naturally, 
it  cannot  be  the  principle  whereby  it  is  communicated  to 
something  else:  thus  the  intention  of  colour  which  is  in  the 
pupil,  cannot  make  a  thing  white;  nor  indeed  can  anything 
enlightened  or  heated  give  heat  or  light  to  something  else; 
for  if  they  could,  enlightening  and  heating  would  go  on  to 
infinity.  But  the  light  of  glory,  whereby  God  is  seen,  is  in 
God  perfectly  and  naturally;  whereas  in  any  creature,  it  is 
imperfectly  and  by  likeness  or  participation.  Consequently 
no  creature  can  communicate  its  Happiness  to  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  A  happy  angel  enlightens  the  intellect  of  a 
man  or  of  a  lower  angel,  as  to  certain  notions  of  the  Divine 
works:  but  not  as  to  the  vision  of  the  Divine  Essence,  as 
was  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  CVI.,  A.  i) :  since  in  order 
to  see  this,  all  are  immediately  enlightened  by  God. 

Seventh  Article. 

whether  any  good  works  are  necessary  that  man  may 
receive  happiness  from  god  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  no  works  of  man  are  necessary 
that  he  may  obtain  Happiness  from  God.  For  since  God 
is  an  agent  of  infinite  power,  He  requires  before  acting, 
neither  matter,  nor  disposition  of  matter,  but  can  forthwith 
produce  the  whole  effect.  But  man's  works,  since  they  are 
not  required  for  Happiness,  as  the  efficient  cause  thereof,  as 
stated  above  (A.  6),  can  be  required  only  as  dispositions 
thereto.  Therefore  God  Who  does  not  require  dispositions 
before  acting,  bestows  Happiness,  without  any  previous  works.' 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  just  as  God  is  the  immediate  cause  of 
Happiness,  so  is  He  the  immediate  cause  of  nature.  But 
when  God  first  estabhshed  nature,  He  produced  creatures 

II.  I  6 


82  QUESTION  V 

without  any  previous  disposition  or  action  on  the  part  of 
the  creature,  but  made  each  one  perfect  forthwith  in  its 
species.  Therefore  it  seems  that  He  bestows  Happiness  on 
man  without  any  previous  works. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  iv.  6)  that  Happi- 
ness is  of  the  man  to  whom  God  reputeth  justice  without  works. 
Therefore  no  works  of  man  are  necessary  for  attaining 
Happiness. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (John  xiii.  17) :  If  you  know 
these  things,  you  shall  be  blessed  if  you  do  them.  Therefore 
Happiness  is  obtained  through  works. 

/  answer  that,   Rectitude  of  the  will,    as  stated   above 
(Q.  IV.,  A.  4),  is  necessary  for  Happiness;  since  it  is  nothing 
else  than  the  right  order  of  the  will  to  the  last  end;  which 
right  order  is  necessary  for  obtaining  the  end,  just  as  the 
right  disposition  of  matter,  in  order  to  receive  the  form. 
But  this  does  not  prove  that  any  work  of  man  need  precede 
his  Happiness:  for  God  could  make  a  will  having  a  right 
tendency  to  the  end,  and  at  the  same  time  attaining  the 
end;  just  as  sometimes  He  disposes  matter  and  at  the  same 
time  introduces  the  form.     But  the  order  of  Divine  wisdom 
demands  that  it  should  not  be  thus;  for  as  it  is  stated  in 
De  Ccelo  ii.,  of  those  things  that  have  a  natural  capacity  for 
the  perfect  good,  one  has  it  without  movement,  some  by  one 
movement,  some  by  several.     Now  to  possess  the  perfect  good 
without  movement,  belongs  to  that  which  has  it  naturally : 
and  to  have  Happiness  naturally  belongs  to  God  alone. 
Therefore  it  belongs  to  God  alone  not  to  be  moved  towards 
Happiness  by  any  previous  operation.     Now  since  Happi- 
ness surpasses  every  created  nature,  no  pure  creature  can 
becomingly    gain    Happiness,    without    the    movement    of 
operation,  whereby  it  tends  thereto.     But  the  angel,  who 
is  above  man  in  the  natural  order,  obtained  it,  according 
to  the  order  of  Divine  wisdom,   by  one  movement  of  a 
meritorious  work;  whereas  man  obtains  it  by  many  move- 
ments of  works  which  are  called  merits.     Wherefore  also 
according  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  i.),  happiness  is  the 
reward  of  works  of  virtue. 


THE  ATTAINMENT  OF  HAPPINESS  83 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Works  are  necessary  to  man  in  order  to 
gain  Happiness;  not  on  account  of  the  insufficiency  of  the 
Divine  power  which  bestows  Happiness,  but  that  the  order 
in  things  be  observed. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  God  produced  the  first  creatures  so  that 
they  were  perfect  forthwith;  without  any  previous  disposi- 
tion or  operation  of  the  creature;  because  He  instituted  the 
individuals  of  the  various  species,  that  through  them  nature 
might  be  propagated  to  their  progeny.  In  Hke  manner, 
because  Happiness  was  to  be  bestowed  on  others  through 
Christ,  Who  is  God  and  Man,  Who,  according  to  Heb.  ii.  10, 
had  brought  many  children  into  glory ;  therefore,  from  the 
very  beginning  of  His  conception,  His  soul  was  happy, 
without  any  previous  meritorious  operation.  But  this  is 
peculiar  to  Him:  for  Christ's  merit  avails  baptized  children 
for  the  gaining  of  Happiness,  though  they  have  no  merits 
of  their  own;  because  by  Baptism  they  are  made  members 
of  Christ. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  Apostle  is  speaking  of  the  Happiness  of 
Hope,  which  is  bestowed  on  us  by  sanctifying  grace,  that 
is  not  given  on  account  of  previous  works.  For  grace  is 
not  a  term  of  movement,  as  Happiness  is;  rather  is  it  the 
principle  of  the  movement  that  tends  towards  Happiness. 

Eighth  Article, 
whether  every  man  desires  happiness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  not  all  desire  Happiness.  For 
no  man  can  desire  what  he  knows  not ;  since  the  apprehended 
good  is  the  object  of  the  appetite  {De  Anima  iii.).  But 
many  know  not  what  Happiness  is.  This  is  evident  from 
the  fact  that,  as  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  xiii.),  sOme 
thought  that  Happiness  consists  in  pleasures  of  the  body;  some, 
in  a  virtue  of  the  soul;  some,  in  other  things.  Therefore  not 
all  desire  Happiness. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  essence  of  Happiness  is  the  vision 
of  the  Divine  Essence,  as  stated  above  (Q.  III.,  A.  8).     But 


84  QUESTION  V 

some  consider  it  impossible  for  man  to  see  the  Divine 
Essence;  wherefore  they  desire  it  not.  Therefore  all  men 
do  not  desire  Happiness. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  {De  Trin.  xiii.)  that 
happy  is  he  who  has  all  he  desires,  and  desires  nothing  amiss. 
But  all  do  not  desire  this;  for  some  desire  certain  things 
amiss,  and  yet  they  wish  to  desire  such  things.  Therefore 
all  do  not  desire  Happiness. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Trin.  xiii.) :  //  that 
actor  had  said :  *  You  all  wish  to  he  happy  ;  you  do  not  wish 
to  he  unhappy,'  he  would  have  said  that  which  none  would 
have  failed  to  acknowledge  in  his  will.  Therefore  ever^^one 
desires  to  be  happy. 

I  answer  that,  Happiness  can  be  considered  in  two  ways. 
First  according  to  the  general  notion  of  happiness :  and  thus, 
of  necessity,  every  man  desires  happiness.  For  the  general 
notion  of  happiness  consists  in  the  perfect  good,  as  stated 
above  (AA.  3,  4).  But  since  good  is  the  object  of  the  will, 
the  perfect  good  of  a  man  is  that  which  entirely  satisfies 
his  will.  Consequently  to  desire  happiness  is  nothing  else 
than  to  desire  that  one's  will  be  satisfied.  And  this  every- 
one desires.  Secondly  we  may  speak  of  Happiness  accord- 
ing to  its  specific  notion,  as  to  that  in  which  it  consists. 
A  And  thus  all  do  not  know  Happiness;  because  they  know 
not  in  what  thing  the  general  notion  of  happiness  is  found. 
And  consequently,  in  this  respect,  not  all  desire  it.  Where- 
fore the  reply  to  the  first  Objection  is  clear. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Since  the  will  follows  the  apprehension  of 
the  intellect  or  reason;  just  as  it  happens  that  where  there 
is  no  real  distinction,  there  may  be  a  distinction  according 
to  the  consideration  of  reason;  so  does  it  happen  that  one 
and  the  same  thing  is  desired  in  one  way,  and  not  desired 
in  another.  So  that  happiness  may  be  considered  as  the 
final  and  perfect  good,  which  is  the  general  notion  of  happi- 
ness: and  thus  the  will  naturally  and  of  necessity  tends 
thereto,  as  stated  above.  Again  it  can  be  considered  under 
other  special  aspects,  either  on  the  part  of  the  operation 
itself,  or  on  the  part  of  the  operating  power,  or  on  the  part 


r 


THE  ATTAINMENT  OF  HAPPINESS  85 

of  the  object;  and  thus  the  will  does  not  tend  thereto  of 
necessity. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  definition  of  Happiness  given  by 
some, — Happy  is  the  man  that  has  all  he  desires,  or,  whose 
every  wish  is  fulfilled,  is  a  good  and  adequate  definition,  if 
it  be  understood  in  a  certain  way ;  but  an  inadequate  defini- 
tion if  understood  in  another.  For  if  we  understand  it 
simply  of  all  that  man  desires  by  his  natural  appetite,  thus 
it  is  true  that  he  who  has  all  that  he  desires,  is  happy: 
since  nothing  satisfies  man's  natural  desire,  except  the 
perfect  good  which  is  Happiness.  But  if  we  understand  it 
of  those  things  that  man  desires  according  to  the  apprehen- 
sion of  the  reason,  thus  it  does  not  belong  to  Happiness,  to 
have  certain  things  that  man  desires;  rather  does  it  belong 
to  unhappiness,  in  so  far  as  the  possession  of  such  things 
hinders  man  from  having  all  that  he  desires  naturally ;  thus 
it  is  that  reason  sometimes  accepts  as  true  things  that  are 
a  hindrance  to  the  knowledge  of  truth.  And  it  was  through 
taking  this  into  consideration  that  Augustine  added  so  as  to 
include  perfect  Happiness, — that  he  desires  nothing  amiss  : 
although  the  first  part  suffices  if  rightly  understood,  to  wit, 
that  happy  is  he  who  has  all  he  desires. 


QUESTION  VI. 

OF  THE  VOLUNTARY  AND  THE  INVOLUNTARY. 

{In  Eight  Articles.) 

Since  therefore  Happiness  is  to  be  gained  by  means  of 
certain  acts,  we  must  in  due  sequence  consider  human  acts, 
in  order  to  know  by  what  acts  we  may  obtain  Happiness, 
and  by  what  acts  we  are  prevented  from  obtaining  it.  But 
because  operations  and  acts  are  concerned  with  things 
singular,  consequently  all  practical  knowledge  is  incomplete 
without  it  take  account  of  things  in  detail.  The  study  of 
Morals,  therefore,  since  it  treats  of  human  acts,  should 
consider  first  the  general  principles;  and  secondly  matters 
of  detail. 

In  treating  of  the  general  principles,  the  points  that 
offer  themselves  for  our  consideration  are — (i)  human  acts 
themselves;  (2)  their  principles.  Now  of  human  acts  some 
are  proper  to  man;  others  are  common  to  man  and  animals. 
And  since  Happiness  is  man's  proper  good,  those  acts  which 
are  proper  to  man  have  a  closer  connection  with  Happiness 
than  have  those  which  are  common  to  man  and  the  other 
animals.  First,  then,  we  must  consider  those  acts  which 
are  proper  to  man;  secondly,  those  acts  which  are  common 
to  man  and  the  other  animals,  and  are  called  Passions. 
The  first  of  these  points  offers  a  twofold  consideration: 
(i)  What  makes  a  human  act  ?  (2)  What  distinguishes 
human  acts  ? 

And  since  these  acts  are  properly  called  human,  which 
are  voluntary,  because  the  will  is  the  rational  appetite, 
which  is  proper  to  man;  we  must  consider  acts  in  so  far  as 
they  are  voluntary. 

86 


VOLUNTARY  AND  INVOLUNTARY      S7 

First,  then,  we  must  consider  the  voluntary  and  involun- 
tary in  general;  secondly,  those  acts  which  are  voluntary, 
as  being  elicited  by  the  will,  and  as  issuing  from  the  will 
immediately;  thirdly,  those  acts  which  are  voluntary,  as 
being  commanded  by  the  will,  which  issue  from  the  will 
through  the  medium  of  the  other  powers. 

And  because  voluntary  acts  have  certain  circumstances, 
according  to  which  we  form  our  judgment  concerning  them, 
we  must  first  consider  the  voluntary  and  the  involuntary, 
and  afterwards,  the  circumstances  of  those  acts  which  are 
found  to  be  voluntary  or  involuntary.  Under  the  first 
head  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  there 
is  anything  voluntary  in  human  acts  ?  (2)  Whether  in 
irrational  animals  ?  (3)  Whether  there  can  be  voluntariness 
without  any  action  ?  (4)  Whether  violence  can  be  done  to 
the  will  ?  (5)  Whether  violence  causes  involuntariness  ? 
(6)  Whether  fear  causes  involuntariness  ?  (7)  Whether  con- 
cupiscence causes  involuntariness  ?  (8)  Whether  ignorance 
causes  involuntariness  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  there  is  anything  voluntary  in  human 

ACTS  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  is  nothing  voluntary  in 
human  acts.  For  that  is  voluntary  which  has  its  principle 
within  itself,  as  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius,  De  Natura 
Horn,  xxxii.),  Damascene  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.),  and 
Aristotle  (Ethic,  iii.)  declare.  But  the  principle  of  human 
acts  is  not  in  man  himself,  but  outside  him:  since  man's 
appetite  is  moved  to  act,  by  the  appetible  object  which  is 
outside  him,  and  is  as  a  mover  unmoved  (De  Anima  iii.). 
Therefore  there  is  nothing  voluntary  in  human  acts. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  (Phys.  viii.)  proves  that 
in  animals  no  new  movement  arises  that  is  not  preceded  by 
a  motion  from  without.  But  all  human  acts  are  new,  since 
none  is  eternal.     Consequently,  the  principle  of  all  human 


8S  QUESTION  VI 

acts  is  from  without :  and  therefore  there  is  nothing  volun- 
tary in  them. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  he  that  acts  voluntarily,  can  act  of 
himself.  But  this  is  not  true  of  man;  for  it  is  written 
(John  XV.  5):  Without  Me  you  can  do  nothing.  Therefore 
there  is  nothing  voluntary  in  human  acts. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.) 
that  the  voluntary  is  an  act  consisting  in  a  rational  operation. 
Now  such  are  human  acts.  Therefore  there  is  something 
voluntary  in  human  acts. 

I  answer  that,  There  must  needs  be  something  voluntary 
in  human  acts.     In  order  to  make  this  clear,  we  must  take 
note  that  the  principle  of  some  acts  or  movements  is  within 
the  agent,  or  that  which  is  moved;  whereas  the  principle 
of  some  movements  or  acts  is  outside.     For  when  a  stone 
is  moved  upwards,  the  principle  of  this  movement  is  outside 
the  stone:  whereas  when  it  is  moved  downwards,  the  prin- 
ciple of  this  movement  is  in  the  stone.     Now  of  those  things 
that  are  moved  by  an  intrinsic  principle,  some  move  them- 
selves, some  not.     For  since  every  agent  or  thing  moved, 
acts  or  is  moved  for  an  end,  as  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  2); 
those  are  perfectly  moved  by  an  intrinsic  principle,  whose 
intrinsic  principle  is  one  not  only  of  movement  but  of 
movement  for  an  end.     Now  in  order  for  a  thing  to  be  done 
for  an  end,  some  knowledge  of  the  end  is  necessary.     There- 
fore, whatever  so  acts  or  is  so  moved  by  an  intrinsic  prin- 
ciple, that  it  has  some  knowledge  of  the  end,  has  within 
itself  the  principle  of  its  act,  so  that  it  not  only  acts,  but  acts 
for  an  end.     On  the  other  hand,  if  a  thing  has  no  know- 
ledge of  the  end,  even  though  it  have  an  intrinsic  principle 
of  action  or  movement,  nevertheless  the  principle  of  acting 
or  being  moved  for  an  end  is  not  in  that  thing,  but  in  some- 
thing else,  by  which  the  principle  of  its  action  towards  an 
end  is  imprinted  on  it.     Wherefore  sucWike  things  are  not 
said  to  move  themselves,  but  to  be  moved  by  others.     And 
consequently,  since  both  are  from  an  intrinsic  principle,  to 
wit,  that  they  act  and  that  they  act  for  an  end,  the  move- 
ments of  such  things  are  said  to  be  voluntary :  for  the  word 


VOLUNTARY  AND  INVOLUNTARY      89 

voluntary  implies  that  their  movements  and  acts  are  from 
their  own  indination.  Hence  it  is  that,  according  to  the 
definitions  of  Aristotle,  Gregory  of  Nyssa,  and  Damascene,* 
the  voluntary  is  defined  not  only  as  having  a  principle 
within  the  agent,  but  also  as  implying  knowledge.  There- 
fore, since  man  especially  knows  the  end  of  his  work,  and 
moves  himself,  in  his  acts  especially  is  the  voluntary  to  be 
found. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Not  every  principle  is  a  first  principle. 
Therefore,  although  it  is  essential  to  the  voluntary  act  that 
its  principle  be  within  the  agent,  nevertheless  it  is  not 
contrary  to  the  nature  of  the  voluntary  act  that  this  intrinsic 
principle  be  caused  or  moved  by  an  extrinsic  principle: 
because  it  is  not  essential  to  the  voluntary  act  that  its  in- 
trinsic principle  be  a  first  principle. — Yet  again  it  must  be 
observed  that  a  principle  of  movement  may  happen  to  be 
first  in  a  genus,  but  not  first  simply:  thus  in  the  genus  of 
things  subject  to  alteration,  the  first  principle  of  alteration 
is  a  heavenly  body,  which  nevertheless  is  not  the  first  mover 
simply,  but  is  moved  locally  by  a  higher  mover.  And  so 
the  intrinsic  principle  of  the  voluntary  act,  i.e.,  the  cogni- 
tive and  appetitive  power,  is  the  first  principle  in  the  genus 
of  appetitive  movement,  although  it  is  moved  by  an  ex- 
trinsic principle  according  to  other  species  of  movement. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  New  movements  in  animals  are  indeed  pre- 
ceded by  a  motion  from  without;  and  this  in  two  respects. 
First,  in  so  far  as  by  means  of  an  extrinsic  motion  an 
animal's  senses  are  confronted  with  something  sensible, 
which,  on  being  apprehended,  moves  the  appetite.  Thus 
a  lion,  on  seeing  a  stag  in  movement  and  coming  towards 
him,  begins  to  be  moved  towards  the  stag. — Secondly,  in  so 
far  as  some  extrinsic  motion  produces  a  physical  change  in 
an  animal's  body,  as  in  the  case  of  cold  or  heat;  and  through 
the  body  being  thus  affected  by  the  motion  of  an  outward 
body,  the  sensitive  appetite  which  is  the  power  of  a  bodily 
organ,  is  also  moved  indirectly ;  thus  it  happens  that  through 
some  alteration  in  the  body  the  appetite  is  roused  to  the 

*  See  objection  i. 


90  QUESTION  VI 

desire  of  something.  But  this  is  not  contrary  to  the  nature 
of  voluntariness,  as  stated  above  {ad  i),  for  such  movements 
caused  by  an  extrinsic  principle  are  of  another  genus  of 
movement. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  God  moves  man  to  act,  not  only  by  pro- 
posing the  appetible  to  the  senses,  or  by  effecting  a  change 
in  his  body,  but  also  by  moving  the  will  itself ;  because  every 
movement  either  of  the  will  or  of  nature,  proceeds  from  God 
as  the  First  Mover.  And  just  as  it  is  not  incompatible 
with  nature  that. the  natural  movement  be  from  God  as 
the  First  Mover,  inasmuch  as  nature  is  an  instrument  of 
God  moving  it:  so  it  is  not  contrary  to  the  essence  of  a 
voluntary  act,  that  it  proceed  from  God,  inasmuch  as  the 
will  is  moved  by  God.  Nevertheless  both  natural  and 
voluntary  movements  have  this  in  common,  that  it  is  essen- 
tial that  they  should  proceed  from  a  principle  within  the 
agent. 

Second  Article. 

whether  there  is  anything  voluntary  in  irrational 

ANIMALS  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  is  nothing  voluntary  in 
irrational  animals.  For  a  thing  is  called  voluntary  from 
voluntas  (will).  Now  since  the  will  is  in  the  reason  (De 
Anima  iii.),  it  cannot  be  in  irrational  animals.  Therefore 
neither  is  there  anything  voluntary  in  them. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  according  as  human  acts  are  voluntary, 
man  is  said  to  be  master  of  his  actions.  But  irrational 
animals  are  not  masters  of  their  actions ;  for  they  act  not ; 
rather  are  they  acted  upon,  as  Damascene  says  [De  Fide 
Orthod.  ii.).  Therefore  there  is  no  such  thing  as  a  volun- 
tary act  in  irrational  animals. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Damascene  says  (ihid.)  that  voluntary 
acts  lead  to  praise  and  blame.  But  neither  praise  nor  blame 
is  due  to  the  acts  of  irrational  animals.  Therefore  such 
acts  are  not  voluntary. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.)  that 


^ 


VOLUNTARY  AND  INVOLUNTARY     91 

both  children  and  irrational  animals  participate  in  the  volun- 
tary. The  same  is  said  by  Damascene  [loc.  cit.)  and  Gregory 
of  Nyssa  (Nemesius,  De  Nat.  Horn,  xxxii.). 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  it  is  essential  to  the 
voluntary  act  that  its  principle  be  within  the  agent,  together 
with  some  knowledge  of  the  end.  Now  knowledge  of  the 
end  is  twofold;  perfect  and  imperfect.  Perfect  knowledge 
of  the  end  consists  in  not  only  apprehending  the  thing 
which  is  the  end,  but  also  in  knowing  it  under  the  aspect  of 
end,  and  the  relationship  of  the  means  to  that  end.  And 
such  knowledge  befits  none  but  the  rational  nature. — But 
imperfect  knowledge  of  the  end  consists  in  mere  apprehen- 
sion of  the  end,  without  knowing  it  under  the  aspect  of 
end,  or  the  relationship  of  an  act  to  the  end.  Such  know- 
ledge of  the  end  is  exercised  by  irrational  animals,  through 
their  senses  and  their  natural  estimative  power. 

Consequently  perfect  knowledge  of  the  end  leads  to  the 
perfect  voluntary;  inasmuch  as,  having  apprehended  the 
end,  a  man  can,  from  deliberating  about  the  end  and  the 
means  thereto,  be  moved,  or  not,  to  gain  that  end. — But 
imperfect  knowledge  of  the  end  leads  to  the  imperfect 
voluntary;  inasmuch  as,  the  agent  apprehends  the  end,  but 
does  not  deliberate,  and  is  moved  to  the  end  at  once.  Where- 
fore the  voluntary  in  its  perfection  befits  none  but  the  ra- 
tional nature:  whereas  the  imperfect  voluntary  is  within 
the  competency  of  even  irrational  animals. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  will  is  the  name  of  the  rational  appetite; 
and  consequently  it  cannot  be  in  things  devoid  of  reason. 
But  the  word  voluntary  is  derived  from  voluntas  {will), 
through  being  applied  to  those  things  in  which  there  is 
some  participation  of  will,  by  way  of  likeness  thereto.  It 
is  thus  that  voluntary  action  is  attributed  to  irrational 
animals,  in  so  far  as  they  are  moved  to  an  end,  through 
some  kind  of  knowledge. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  fact  that  man  is  master  of  his  actions, 
is  due  to  his  being  able  to  deliberate  about  them:  for  since 
the  deliberating  reason  is  indifferently  disposed  to  opposite 
things,   the  will  can  be  inclined  to  either.     But  it  is  not 


92  QUESTION  VI 

thus  that  voluntariness  is  in  irrational  animals,  as  stated 
above. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Praise  and  blame  are  the  result  of  the 
voluntary  act,  wherein  is  the  perfect  voluntary;  such  as  is 
not  to  be  found  in  irrational  animals. 


Third  Article, 
whether  there  can  be  voluntariness  without 

ANY  ACT  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  voluntariness  cannot  be  with- 
out any  act.  For  that  is  voluntary  which  proceeds  from 
the  will.  But  nothing  can  proceed  from  the  will,  except 
through  some  act,  at  least  an  act  of  the  will.  Therefore 
there  cannot  be  voluntariness  without  act. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  just  as  one  is  said  to  wish  by  an  act  of 
the  will,  so  when  the  act  of  the  will  ceases,  one  is  said  not 
to  wish.  But  not  to  wish  implies  involuntariness,  which  is 
contrary  to  voluntariness.  Therefore  there  can  be  nothing 
voluntary  when  the  act  of  the  will  ceases. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  knowledge  is  essential  to  the  voluntary, 
as  stated  above  (AA.  i,  2).  But  knowledge  involves  an 
act.     Therefore  voluntariness  cannot  be  without  some  act. 

On  the  contrary,  The  word  voluntary  is  applied  to  that  of 
which  we  are  masters.  Now  we  are  masters  in  respect  of 
to  act  and  not  to  act,  to  will  and  not  to  will.  Therefore 
just  as  to  act  and  to  will  are  voluntary,  so  also  are  not  to 
act  and  not  to  will. 

/  answer  that,  Voluntary  is  what  proceeds  from  the  will. 
Now  one  thing  proceeds  from  another  in  two  ways.  First, 
directly;  in  which  sense  something  proceeds  from  another 
inasmuch  as  this  other  acts;  for  instance,  heating  from  heat. 
Secondly,  indirectly;  in  which  sense  something  proceeds 
from  another  through  this  other  not  acting;  thus  the  sink- 
ing of  a  ship  is  set  down  to  the  helmsman,  from  his  having 
ceased  to  steer. — But  we  must  take  note  that  the  cause  of 
what  follows  from  want  of  action  is  not  always  the  agent 


VOLUNTARY  AND  INVOLUNTARY     93 

as  not  acting ;  but  only  then  when  the  agent  can  and  ought 
to  act.  For  if  the  helmsman  were  unable  to  steer  the  ship, 
or  if  the  ship's  helm  be  not  entrusted  to  him,  the  sinking 
of  the  ship  would  not  be  set  down  to  him,  although  it  might 
be  due  to  his  absence  from  the  helm. 

Since,  then,  the  will  by  willing  and  acting,  is  able,  and  some- 
times ought,  to  hinder  not- willing  and  not-acting;  this  not- 
willing  and  not-acting  is  imputed  to,  as  though  proceeding 
from,  the  will.  And  thus  it  is  that  we  can  have  the  volun- 
tary without  an  act;  sometimes  without  outward  act,  but 
with  an  interior  act ;  for  instance,  when  one  wills  not  to  act ; 
and  sometimes  without  even  an  interior  act,  as  when  one 
does  not  will  to  act. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  We  apply  the  word  voluntary  not  only  to 
that  which  proceeds  from  the  will  directly,  as  from  its 
action;  but  also  to  that  which  proceeds  from  it  indirectly 
as  from  its  inaction. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Not  to  wish  is  said  in  two  senses.  First,  as 
though  it  were  one  word,  and  the  infinitive  of  I-do-not-wish. 
Consequently  just  as  when  I  say  /  do  not  wish  to  read,  the 
sense  is,  /  wish  not  to  read ;  so  not  to  wish  to  read  is  the 
same  as  to  wish  not  to  read,  and  in  this  sense  not  to  wish 
implies  involuntariness. — Secondly  it  is  taken  as  a  sentence: 
and  then  no  act  of  the  will  is  affirmed.  And  in  this  sense 
not  to  wish  does  not  imply  involuntariness. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Voluntariness  requires  an  act  of  knowledge 
in  the  same  way  as  it  requires  an  act  of  will;  namely,  in 
order  that  it  be  in  one's  power  to  consider,  to  wish  and  to 
act.  And  then,  just  as  not  to  wish,  and  not  to  act,  when  it 
is  time  to  wish  and  to  act,  is  voluntary,  so  is  it  voluntary 
not  to  consider. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  violence  can  be  done  to  the  will  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  1.  It  seems  that  violence  can  be  done  to  the  will. 
For  everything  can  be  compelled  by  that  which  is  more 
powerful.     But  there  is  something,   namely,   God,   that  is 


94  QUESTION  VI 

more  powerful  than  the  human  will.     Therefore  it  can  be 
compelled,  at  least  by  Him. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  every  passive  subject  is  compelled  by 
its  active  principle,  when  it  is  changed  by  it.  But  the  will 
is  a  passive  force:  for  it  is  a  mover  moved  (De  Anima  iii.). 
Therefore,  since  it  is  sometimes  moved  by  its  active  prin- 
ciple, it  seems  that  sometimes  it  is  compelled. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  violent  movement  is  that  which  is  con- 
trary to  nature.  But  the  movement  of  the  will  is  sometimes 
contrary  to  nature;  as  is  clear  of  the  will's  movement  to 
sin,  which  is  contrary  to  nature,  as  Damascene  says  (De 
Fide  Orthod.  iv.).  Therefore  the  movement  of  the  will  can 
be  compelled. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [De  Civ.  Dei.  v.)  that 
what  is  done  by  the  will  is  not  done  of  necessity.  Now, 
whatever  is  done  under  compulsion  is  done  of  necessity: 
consequently  what  is  done  by  the  will,  cannot  be  compelled. 
Therefore  the  will  cannot  be  compelled  to  act. 

I  answer  that,  The  act  of  the  will  is  twofold:  one  is  its 
immediate  act;  as  it  were,  elicited  by  it,  namely,  to  wish  ; 
the  other  is  an  act  of  the  will  commanded  by  it,  and  put 
into  execution  by  means  of  some  other  power,  such  as  to 
walk  and  to  speak,  which  are  commanded  by  the  will  to  be 
executed  by  means  of  the  motive  power. 

As  regards  the  commanded  acts  of  the  will,  then,  the 
will  can  suffer  violence,  in  so  far  as  violence  can  prevent 
the  exterior  members  from  executing  the  will's  command. 
But  as  to  the  will's  own  proper  act,  violence  cannot  be  done 
to  the  will. 

The  reason  of  this  is  that  the  act  of  the  will  is  nothing 
else  than  an  inclination  proceeding  from  the  interior  prin- 
ciple of  knowledge:  just  as  the  natural  appetite  is  an  in- 
clination proceeding  from  an  interior  principle  without 
knowledge.  Now  what  is  compelled  or  violent  is  from  an 
exterior  principle.  Consequently  it  is  contrary  to  the 
nature  of  the  will's  own  act,  that  it  should  be  subject  to 
compulsion  or  violence:  just  as  it  is  also  contrary  to  the 
nature  of  a  natural  inclination  or  movement.     For  a  stone 


VOLUNTARY  AND  INVOLUNTARY     95 

may  have  an  upward  movement  from  violence,  but  that 
this  violent  movement  be  from  its  natural  incUnation  is 
impossible.  In  Hke  manner  a  man  may  be  dragged  by 
force :  but  it  is  contrary  to  the  very  notion  of  violence,  that 
he  be  thus  dragged  of  his  own  will. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  God  Who  is  more  powerful  than  the  human 
will,  can  move  the  will  of  man,  according  to  Prov.  xxi.  i: 
The  heart  of  the  king  is  in  the  hand  of  the  Lord  ;  whithersoever 
He  will  He  shall  turn  it.  But  if  this  were  by  compulsion, 
it  would  no  longer  be  by  an  act  of  the  will,  nor  would  the 
will  itself  be  moved,  but  something  else  against  the  will. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  It  is  not  always  a  violent  movement,  when 
a  passive  subject  is  moved  by  its  active  principle;  but  only 
when  this  is  done  against  the  interior  inclination  of  the 
passive  subject.  Otherwise  every  alteration  and  genera- 
tion of  simple  bodies  would  be  unnatural  and  violent: 
whereas  they  are  natural  by  reason  of  the  natural  interior 
aptitude  of  the  matter  or  subject  to  such  a  disposition.  In 
like  manner  when  the  will  is  moved,  according  to  its  own 
inclination,  by  the  appetible  object,  this  movement  is  not 
violent  but  voluntary. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  That  to  which  the  will  tends  by  sinning, 
although  in  reality,  it  is  evil  and  contrary  to  the  rational 
nature,  nevertheless  is  apprehended  as  something  good  and 
suitable  to  nature,  in  so  far  as  it  is  suitable  to  man  by  reason 
of  some  pleasurable  sensation  or  some  vicious  habit. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  violence  causes  involuntariness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  violence  does  not  cause  involun- 
tariness.  For  we  speak  of  voluntariness  and  involuntari- 
ness  in  respect  of  the  will.  But  violence  cannot  be  done  to 
the  will,  as  shown  above  (A.  4).  Therefore  violence  cannot 
cause  involuntariness. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  that  which  is  done  involuntarily  is  done 
with   grief,    as   Damascene   (De  Fide  Orthod.   ii.)    and   the 


96  QUESTION  VI 

Philosopher  {Ethic,  hi.)  say.  But  sometimes  a  man  suffers 
compulsion  without  being  grieved  thereby.  Therefore  vio- 
lence does  not  cause  involuntariness. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  what  is  from  the  will  cannot  be  involun- 
tary. But  some  violent  actions  proceed  from  the  will:  for 
instance,  when  a  man  with  a  heavy  body  goes  upwards ;  or 
when  a  man  contorts  his  limbs  in  a  way  contrary  to  their 
natural  flexibility.  Therefore  violence  does  not  cause  in- 
voluntariness. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  {Ethic,  ii.)  and  Dama- 
scene {loc.  cit.)  say  that  things  done  under  compulsion  are 
involuntary. 

I  answer  that,  Violence  is  directly  opposed  to  the  volun- 
tary, as  likewise  to  the  natural.  For  the  voluntary  and  the 
natural  have  this  in  common,  that  both  are  from  an  intrinsic 
principle;  whereas  violence  is  from  an  extrinsic  principle. 
And  for  this  reason,  just  as  in  things  devoid  of  knowledge, 
violence  effects  something  against  nature;  so  in  things  en- 
dowed with  knowledge,  it  effects  something  against  the  will. 
Now  that  which  is  against  nature  is  said  to  be  unnatural; 
and  in  like  manner  that  which  is  against  the  will  is  said  to 
be  involuntary.     Therefore  violence  causes  involuntariness. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  involuntary  is  opposed  to  the  volun- 
tary. Now  it  has  been  said  (A.  4)  that  not  only  the  act, 
which  proceeds  immediately  from  the  will,  is  called  volun- 
tary, but  also  the  act  commanded  by  the  will.  Conse- 
quently, as  to  the  act  which  proceeds  immediately  from  the 
will,  violence  cannot  be  done  the  will,  as  stated  above  {ibid.) : 
wherefore  violence  cannot  make  that  act  involuntary.  But 
as  to  the  commanded  act,  the  will  can  suffer  violence:  and 
consequently  in  this  respect  violence  causes  involuntariness. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  As  that  is  said  to  be  natural,  which  is 
according  to  the  inclination  of  nature;  so  that  is  said  to  be 
voluntary,  which  is  according  to  the  inclination  of  the  will. 
Now  a  thing  is  said  to  be  natural  in  two  ways.  First, 
because  it  is  from  nature  as  from  an  active  principle:  thus 
it  is  natural  for  fire  to  produce  heat.  Secondly,  according 
to  a  passive  principle;  because,  to  wit,  there  is  a  natural 


VOLUNTARY  AND  INVOLUNTARY     97 

inclination  to  receive  an  action  from  an  extrinsic  principle: 
thus  the  movement  of  the  heavens  is  said  to  be  natural,  by 
reason  of  the  natural  aptitude  in  a  heavenly  body  to  receive 
such  movement;  although  the  cause  of  that  movement  is 
a  voluntary  agent.  In  like  manner  an  act  is  said  to  be 
voluntary  in  two  ways.  First,  in  regard  to  action,  for 
instance,  when  one  wishes  to  act:  secondly,  in  regard  to 
passion,  as  when  one  wishes  to  be  passive  to  another. 
Hence  when  action  is  brought  to  bear  on  something,  by  an 
extrinsic  agent,  as  long  as  the  will  to  suffer  that  action 
remains  in  the  passive  subject,  there  is  not  violence  simply: 
for  although  the  patient  does  nothing  by  way  of  action,  he 
does  something  by  being  willing  to  suffer.  Consequently 
this  cannot  be  called  involuntary. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  the  Philosopher  says  (Phys.  viii.)  the 
movement  of  an  animal,  whereby  at  times  an  animal  is 
moved  against  the  natural  inclination  of  the  body,  although 
it  is  not  natural  to  the  body,  is  nevertheless  somewhat 
natural  to  the  animal,  to  which  it  is  natural  to  be  moved 
according  to  its  appetite.  Accordingly  this  is  violent,  not 
simply  but  in  a  certain  respect. — The  same  remark  applies 
in  the  case  of  one  who  contorts  his  limbs  in  a  way  that  is 
contrary  to  their  natural  disposition.  For  this  is  violent 
in  a  certain  respect,  i.e.,  as  to  that  particular  limb;  but  not 
simply,  i.e.,  as  to  the  man  himself. 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  fear  causes  involuntariness  simply  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  fear  causes  involuntariness 
simply.  For  just  as  violence  regards  that  which  is  con- 
trary to  the  will  at  the  time,  so  fear  regards  a  future  evil 
which  is  repugnant  to  the  will.  But  violence  causes  in- 
voluntariness simply.  Therefore  fear  too  causes  involun- 
tariness simply. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  that  which  is  such  of  itself,  remains  such, 
whatever  be  added  to  it:  thus  what  is  hot  of  itself,  as  long 

II.  I  7 


98  QUESTION  VI 

as  it  remains,  is  still  hot,  whatever  be  added  to  it.  But 
that  which  is  done  through  fear,  is  involuntary  in  itself. 
Therefore,  even  with  the  addition  of  fear,  it  is  involuntary. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  that  which  is  such,  subject  to  a  condi- 
tion, is  such  in  a  certain  respect;  whereas  what  is  such, 
without  any  condition,  is  such  simply :  thus  what  is  neces- 
sary, subject  to  a  condition,  is  necessary  in  some  respect: 
but  what  is  necessary  absolutely,  is  necessary  simply.  But 
that  which  is  done  through  fear,  is  absolutely  involuntary; 
and  is  not  voluntary,  save  under  a  condition,  namely,  in 
order  that  the  evil  feared  may  be  avoided.  Therefore  that 
which  is  done  through  fear,  is  involuntary  simply. 

On,  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius,  De  Nat. 
Horn.  XXX.)  and  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iii.)  say  that  such 
things  as  are  done  through  fear  are  voluntary  rather  than 
involuntary. 

I  answer  that,  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.)  and 
likewise  Gregory  of  Nyssa  in  his  book  on  Man  (Nemesius, 
loc.  cit.),  such  things  as  are  done  through  fear  are  of  a  mixed 
character,  being  partly  voluntary  and  partly  involuntary. 
For  that  which  is  done  through  fear,  considered  in  itself,  is 
not  voluntary;  but  it  becomes  voluntary  in  this  particular 
case,  in  order,  namely,  to  avoid  the  evil  feared. 

But  if  the  matter  be  considered  aright,  such  things  are 
voluntary  rather  than  involuntary;  for  they  are  voluntary 
simply,  but  involuntary  in  a  certain  respect.  For  a  thing 
is  said  to  be  simply,  according  as  it  is  in  act;  but  according 
as  it  is  only  in  the  apprehension,  it  is  not  simply,  but  in  a 
certain  respect.  Now  that  which  is  done  through  fear,  is 
in  act  in  so  far  as  it  is  done.  For,  since  acts  are  concerned 
with  singulars;  and  the  singular,  as  such,  is  here  and  now^, 
that  which  is  done  is  in  act,  in  so  far  as  it  is  here  and  now 
and  under  other  individuating  circumstances.  And  that 
which  is  done  through  fear,  is  voluntary,  inasmuch  as  it 
is  here  and  now,  that  is  to  say,  in  so  far  as,  under  the  cir- 
cumstances, it  hinders  a  greater  evil  which  was  feared ;  thus 
the  throwing  of  the  cargo  into  the  sea  becomes  voluntary 
during  the  storm,  through  fear  of  the  danger:  wherefore  it 


VOLUNTARY  AND  INVOLUNTARY      99 

is  clear  that  it  is  voluntary  simply.  And  hence  it  is  that 
what  is  done  out  of  fear  is  essentially  voluntary,  because  its 
principle  is  within. — But  if  we  consider  what  is  done  through 
fear,  as  outside  this  particular  case,  and  inasmuch  as  it  is 
repugnant  to  the  will,  this  is  merely  a  consideration  of  the 
mind.  And  consequently  what  is  done  through  fear  is  in- 
voluntary, considered  in  that  respect,  that  is  to  say,  outside 
the  actual  circumstances  of  the  case. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Things  done  through  fear  and  compulsion, 
differ  not  only  according  to  present  and  future  time,  but 
also  in  this,  that  the  will  does  not  consent,  but  is  moved 
entirely  counter  to  that  which  is  done  through  compulsion: 
whereas  what  is  done  through  fear,  becomes  voluntary, 
because  the  will  is  moved  towards  it,  albeit  not  for  its  own 
sake,  but  on  account  of  something  else,  that  is,  in  order  to 
avoid  an  evil  which  is  feared.  For  the  conditions  of  a 
voluntary  act  are  satisfied,  if  it  be  done  on  account  of 
something  else  voluntary:  since  the  voluntary  is  not  only 
what  we  wish,  for  its  own  sake,  as  an  end,  but  also  what 
we  wish  for  the  sake  of  something  else,  as  an  end.  It  is 
clear  therefore  that  in  what  is  done  from  compulsion,  the 
will  does  nothing  inwardly ;  whereas  in  what  is  done  through 
fear,  the  will  does  something.  Accordingly,  as  Gregory  of 
Nyssa  (Nemesius,  loc.  cit.)  says,  in  order  to  exclude  things 
done  through  fear,  a  violent  action  is  defined  as  not  only 
one,  the  principle  whereof  is  from  without,  but  with  the  addi- 
tion, in  which  he  that  suffers  violence  concurs  not  at  all; 
because  the  will  of  him  that  is  in  fear,  does  concur  somewhat 
in  that  which  he  does  through  fear. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Things  that  are  such  absolutely,  remain 
such,  whatever  be  added  to  them;  for  instance,  a  cold  thing, 
or  a  white  thing:  but  things  that  are  such  relatively,  vary 
according  as  they  are  compared  with  different  things.  For 
what  is  big  in  comparison  with  one  thing,  is  small  in  com- 
parison with  another.  Now  a  thing  is  said  to  be  voluntary, 
not  only  for  its  own  sake,  as  it  were  absolutely ;  but  also  for 
the  sake  of  something  else,  as  it  were  relatively.  Accord- 
ingly, nothing  prevents  a  thing  which  was  not  voluntary  in 


100  QUESTION  VI 

comparison  with  one  thing,  from  becoming  voluntary  when 
compared  with  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  That  which  is  done  through  fear,  is  volun- 
tary without  any  condition,  that  is  to  say,  according  as  it 
is  actually  done :  but  it  is  involuntary,  under  a  certain  con- 
dition, that  is  to  say,  if  such  a  fear  were  not  threatening. 
Consequently,  this  argument  proves  rather  the  opposite. 

Seventh  Article, 
whether  concupiscence  causes  involuntariness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  concupiscence  causes  involun- 
tariness.  For  just  as  fear  is  a  passion,  so  is  concupiscence. 
But  fear  causes  involuntariness  to  a  certain  extent.  There- 
fore concupiscence  does  so  too. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  just  as  the  timid  man  through  fear  acts 
counter  to  that  which  he  proposed,  so  does  the  incontinent, 
through  concupiscence.  But  fear  causes  involuntariness  to 
a  certain  extent.     Therefore  concupiscence  does  so  also. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  knowledge  is  necessary  for  voluntariness. 
But  concupiscence  impairs  knowledge;  for  the  Philosopher 
says  {Ethic,  vi.)  that  delight,  or  the  lust  of  pleasure,  destroys 
the  judgment  of  prudence.  Therefore  concupiscence  causes 
involuntariness. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.): 
The  involuntary  act  deserves  mercy  or  indulgence,  and  is  done 
with  regret.  But  neither  of  these  can  be  said  of  that  which 
is  done  out  of  concupiscence.  Therefore  concupiscence  does 
not  cause  involuntariness. 

/  answer  that,  Concupiscence  does  not  cause  involuntari- 
ness, but  on  the  contrary  makes  something  to  be  voluntary. 
For  a  thing  is  said  to  be  voluntary,  from  the  fact  that  the 
will  is  moved  to  it.  Now  concupiscence  inclines  the  will  to 
desire  the  object  of  concupiscence.  Therefore  the  effect  of 
concupiscence  is  to  make  something  to  be  voluntary  rather 
than  involuntary. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Fear  regards  evil,  but  concupiscence  regards 


VOLUNTARY  AND  INVOLUNTARY     loi 

good.  Now  evil  of  itself  is  counter  to  the  will,  whereas  good 
harmonizes  with  the  will.  Therefore  fear  has  a  greater 
tendency  than  concupiscence  to  cause  involuntariness. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  He  who  acts  from  fear  retains  the  repug- 
nance of  the  will  to  that  which  he  does,  considered  in  itself. 
But  he  that  acts  from  concupiscence,  e.g.,  an  incontinent 
man,  does  not  retain  his  former  will  whereby  he  repudiated 
the  object  of  his  concupiscence;  for  his  will  is  changed,  so 
that  he  desires  that  which  previously  he  repudiated.  Ac- 
cordingly, that  which  is  done  out  of  fear  is  involuntary,  to 
a  certain  extent,  but  that  which  is  done  from  concupiscence 
is  nowise  involuntary.  For  the  man  who  yields  to  con- 
cupiscence acts  counter  to  that  which  he  purposed  at  first, 
but  not  counter  to  that  which  he  desires  now;  whereas  the 
timid  man  acts  counter  to  that  which  in  itself  he  desires 
now. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  If  concupiscence  were  to  destroy  know- 
ledge altogether,  as  happens  with  those  whom  concupiscence 
has  rendered  mad,  it  would  follow  that  concupiscence  would 
take  away  voluntariness.  And  yet  properly  speaking  it 
would  not  result  in  the  act  being  involuntary,  because  in 
things  bereft  of  reason,  there  is  neither  voluntary  nor  in- 
voluntary. But  sometimes  in  those  actions  which  are  done 
from  concupiscence,  knowledge  is  not  completely  destroyed, 
because  the  power  of  knowing  is  not  taken  away  entirely, 
but  only  the  actual  consideration  in  some  particular  possible 
act.  Nevertheless,  this  itself  is  voluntary,  according  as  by 
voluntary  we  mean  that  which  is  in  the  power  of  the  will, 
for  example,  not  to  act  or  7iot  to  will,  and  in  like  manner  not 
to  consider  ;  for  the  will  can  resist  the  passion,  as  we  shall 
state  later  on  (Q.  X.,  A.  3;  Q.  LXXVIL,  A.  7). 

Eighth  Article. 

whether  ignorance  causes  involuntariness  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  A  rticle  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  ignorance  does  not  cause  in- 
voluntariness.    For  the  involuntary  act  deserves  pardon,  as 


102  QUESTION  VI 

Damascene  says  {De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.).  But  sometimes  that 
which  is  done  through  ignorance  does  not  deserve  pardon, 
according  to  i  Cor.  xiv.  38 :  If  any  man  know  not,  he  shall 
not  he  known.  Therefore  ignorance  does  not  cause  invohm- 
tariness. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  every  sin  impHes  ignorance;  according  to 
Prov.  xiv.  22 :  They  err,  that  work  evil.  If,  therefore,  ignor- 
ance causes  involuntariness,  it  would  follow  that  every  sin 
is  involuntary :  which  is  opposed  to  the  saying  of  Augustine, 
that  every  sin  is  voluntary  (De  Vera.  Relig.  xiv.). 

Obj.  3.  Further,  involuntariness  is  not  without  sadness,  as 
Damascene  says  [loc.  cit.).  But  some  things  are  done  out  of 
ignorance,  but  without  sadness:  for  instance,  a  man  may 
kill  a  foe,  whom  he  wishes  to  kill,  thinking  at  the  time  that 
he  is  killing  a  stag.  Therefore  ignorance  does  not  cause 
involuntariness. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  (loc.  cit.)  and  the  Philosopher 
(Ethic,  iii.)  say  that  what  is  done  through  ignorance  is  in- 
voluntq,ry. 

I  answer  that,  If  ignorance  cause  involuntariness,  it  is  in 
so  far  as  it  deprives  one  of  knowledge,  which  is  a  necessary 
condition  of  voluntariness,  as  was  declared  above  (A.  i). 
But  it  is  not  every  ignorance  that  deprives  one  of  this 
knowledge.  Accordingly,  we  must  take  note  that  ignorance 
has  a  threefold  relationship  to  the  act  of  the  will:  in  one 
way,  concomitantly ;  in  another,  consequently ;  in  a  third 
way,  antecedently. — Concomitantly ,  when  there  is  ignorance 
of  what  is  done ;  but,  so  that  even  if  it  were  known,  it  would 
be  done.  For  then,  ignorance  does  not  induce  one  to  wish 
this  to  be  done,  but  it  just  happens  that  a  thing  is  at  the 
same  time  done  and  not  known:  thus  in  the  example  given 
(Oh].  3)  a  man  did  indeed  wish  to  kill  his  foe,  but  killed 
him  in  ignorance,  thinking  to  kill  a  stag.  And  ignorance  of 
this  kind,  as  the  Philosopher  states  (Ethic,  iii.),  does  not 
cause  involuntariness,  since  it  is  not  the  cause  of  anything 
that  is  repugnant  to  the  will:  but  it  causes  non-voluntari- 
ness,  since  that  which  is  unknown  cannot  be  actually  willed. 
Ignorance  is  consequent  to  the  act  of  the  will,  in  so  far  as 


VOLUNTARY  AND  INVOLUNTARY     103 

ignorance  itself  is  voluntary :  and  this  happens  in  two  ways, 
in  accordance  with  the  two  aforesaid  modes  of  voluntary 
(A.  3).     First,   because  the  act  of  the  will  is  brought  to 
bear  on  the  ignorance:  as  when  a  man  wishes  not  to  know, 
that  he  may  have  an  excuse  for  sin,  or  that  he  may  not  be 
withheld  from  sin;  according  to  Job  xxi.  14:  We  desire  not 
the   knowledge   of  Thy   ways.     And   this   is   called   affected 
ignorance. — Secondly,   ignorance  is   said   to   be  voluntary, 
when  it  regards  that  which  one  can  and  ought  to  know: 
for  in  this  sense  not  to  act  and  not  to  will  are  said  to  be 
voluntary,  as  stated  above  (A.  3).     And  ignorance  of  this 
kind  happens,  either  when  one  does  not  actually  consider 
what  one  can  and  ought  to  consider; — this  is  called  ignor- 
ance   of   evil    choice,    and    arises    from    some    passion    or 
habit:   or  when  one  does  not  take  the  trouble  to  acquire 
the  knowledge  which  one  ought  to  have;   in  which  sense, 
ignorance    of   the   general   principles    of   law,    which    one 
ought  to  know,  is  voluntary,  as  being  due  to  negligence. — 
Accordingly  if,  in  either  of  these  ways,  ignorance  is  volun- 
tary, it  cannot  cause  involuntariness  simply.     Nevertheless, 
it  causes  involuntariness  in  a  certain  respect,  inasmuch  as  it 
precedes  the  movement  of  the  will  towards  the  act,  which 
movement  would  not  be,  if  there  were  knowledge.     Ignor- 
ance is  antecedent  to  the  act  of  the  will,  when  it  is  not  volun- 
tary, and  yet  is  the  cause  of  man's  willing  what  he  would 
not  will  otherwise.     Thus  a  man  may  be  ignorant  of  some 
circumstance  of  his  act,  which  he  was  not  bound  to  know, 
the  result  being  that  he  does  that  which  he  would  not  do, 
if  he  knew  of  that  circumstance;  for  instance,  a  man,  after 
taking  proper  precaution,  may  not  know  that  someone  is 
coming  along  the  road,  so  that  he  shoots  an  arrow  and  slays 
a  passer-by.     Such  ignorance  causes  involuntariness  simply. 
From  this  may  be  gathered  the  solution  of  the  objections. 
For  the  first  objection  deals  with  ignorance  of  what  a  man 
is  bound  to  know.     The  second,  with  ignorance  of  choice, 
which  is  voluntary  to  a  certain  extent,   as  stated  above. 
The  third,  of  that  ignorance  which  is  concomitant  with  the 
act  of  the  will. 


QUESTION  VII. 

OF  THE  CIRCUMSTANCES  OF  HUMAN  ACTS 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  circumstances  of  human  acts: 
under  which  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  What 
is  a  circumstance  ?  (2)  Whether  a  theologian  should  take 
note  of  the  circumstances  of  human  acts  ?  (3)  How  many 
circumstances  are  there  ?  (4)  Which  are  the  most  impor- 
tant of  them  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  a  circumstance  is  an  accident  of  a  human 

ACT  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  circumstance  is  not  an  acci- 
dent of  a  human  act.  For  Tully  says  [De  Invent.  Rhetor,  i.) 
that  a  circumstance  is  that  from  which  an  orator  adds 
authority  and  strength  to  his  argument.  But  oratorical  argu- 
ments are  derived  principally  from  things  pertaining  to  the 
essence  of  a  thing,  such  as  the  definition,  the  genus,  the 
species,  and  the  like,  from  which  also  Tully  declares  that  an 
orator  should  draw  his  arguments.  Therefore  a  circum- 
stance is  not  an  accident  of  a  human  act. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  to  he  in  is  proper  to  an  accident.  But 
that  which  surrounds  (circumstat)  is  rather  out  than  in. 
Therefore  the  circumstances  are  not  accidents  of  human 
acts. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  an  accident  has  no  accident.  But 
human  acts  themselves  are  accidents.  Therefore  the  cir- 
cumstances are  not  accidents  of  acts. 

104 


CIRCUMSTANCES  OF  HUMAN  ACTS  105 

On  the  contrary,  The  particular  conditions  of  any  singular 
thing  are  called  its  individuating  accidents.  But  the  Philo- 
sopher (Ethic,  iii.)  calls  the  circumstances  particular  things 
(/cad'e/caaTo),  i.e.,  the  particular  conditions  of  each  act. 
Therefore  the  circumstances  are  individual  accidents  of 
human  acts. 

/  answer  that,  Since,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Peri 
Herm.  i.),  words  are  the  signs  of  what  we  understand,  it  must 
needs  be  that  in  naming  things  we  follow  the  process  of 
intellectual  knowledge.  Now  our  intellectual  knowledge 
proceeds  from  the  better  known  to  the  less  known.  Ac- 
cordingly with  us,  names  of  more  obvious  things  are  trans- 
ferred so  as  to  signify  things  less  obvious:  and  hence  it  is 
that,  as  stated  in  Metaph.  x.,  the  notion  of  distance  has  been 
transferred  from  things  that  are  apart  locally,  to  all  kinds  of 
opposition  :  and  in  like  manner  words  that  signify  local 
movement  are  employed  to  designate  all  other  movements, 
because  bodies  which  are  circumscribed  by  place,  are  best 
known  to  us.  And  hence  it  is  that  the  word  circumstance 
has  passed  from  located  things  to  human  acts. 

Now  in  things  located,  that  is  said  to  surround  some- 
thing, which  is  outside  it,  but  touches  it,  or  is  placed  near 
it.  Accordingly,  whatever  conditions  are  outside  the  sub- 
stance of  an  act,  and  yet  in  some  way  touch  the  human 
act,  are  called  circumstances.  Now  what  is  outside  a 
thing's  substance,  while  it  belongs  to  that  thing,  is  called 
its  accident.  Wherefore  the  circumstances  of  human  acts 
should  be  called  their  accidents. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  orator  gives  strength  to  his  argument, 
in  the  first  place,  from  the  substance  of  the  act;  and, 
secondly,  from  the  circumstances  of  the  act.  Thus  a  man 
becomes  indictable,  first,  through  being  guilty  of  murder; 
secondly,  through  having  acted  fraudulently,  or  from 
motives  of  greed,  or  at  a  holy  time  or  place,  and  so 
forth.  And  so  in  the  passage  quoted,  it  is  said  pointedly 
that  the  orator  adds  strength  to  his  argument,  as  though  this 
were  something  secondary. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  thing  is  said  to  be  an  accident  of  some- 


io6  QUESTION  VII 

thing  in  two  ways.  First,  from  being  in  that  thing:  thus, 
whiteness  is  said  to  be  an  accident  of  Socrates.  Secondly, 
because  it  is  together  with  that  thing  in  the  same  subject: 
thus,  whiteness  is  an  accident  of  music,  inasmuch  as  they 
meet  in  the  same  subject,  so  as  to  touch  one  another,  as  it 
were.  And  in  this  sense  circumstances  are  said  to  be  the 
accidents  of  human  acts. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  stated  above  {ad  2),  an  accident  is  said 
to  be  the  accident  of  an  accident,  from  the  fact  that  they 
meet  in  the  same  subject.  But  this  happens  in  two  ways. 
First,  in  so  far  as  two  accidents  are  both  related  to  the 
same  subject,  without  any  relation  to  one  another;  as 
whiteness  and  music  in  Socrates.  Secondly,  when  such 
accidents  are  related  to  one  another;  as  when  the  subject 
receives  one  accident  by  means  of  the  other;  for  instance, 
a  body  receives  colour  by  means  of  its  surface.  And  thus 
also  is  one  accident  said  to  be  in  another;  for  we  speak  of 
colour  as  being  in  the  surface. 

Accordingly,  circumstances  are  related  to  acts  in  both 
these  ways.  For  some  circumstances  that  have  a  relation 
to  acts,  belong  to  the  agent  otherwise  than  through  the  act ; 
as  place  and  condition  of  person:  whereas  others  belong  to 
the  agent  by  reason  of  the  act,  as  the  manner  in  which  the 
act  is  done. 

Second  Article. 

whether  theologians  should  take  note  of  the 
circumstances  of  human  acts  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  theologians  should  not  take 
note  of  the  circumstances  of  human  acts.  Because  theo- 
logians do  not  consider  human  acts  otherwise  than  accord- 
ing to  their  quality  of  good  or  evil.  But  it  seems  that  cir- 
cumstances cannot  give  quality  to  human  acts;  for  a 
thing  is  never  qualified,  formally  speaking,  by  that  which 
is  outside  it;  but  by  that  which  is  in  it.  Therefore 
theologians  should  not  take  note  of  the  circumstances  of 
acts. 


CIRCUMSTANCES  OF  HUMAN  ACTS  107 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  circumstances  are  the  accidents  of  acts. 
But  one  thing  may  be  subject  to  an  infinity  of  accidents; 
hence  the  Philosopher  says  (Metaph.  vi.)  that  no  art  or 
science  considers  accidental  being,  except  only  the  art  of 
sophistry.  Therefore  the  theologian  has  not  to  consider 
circumstances. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  consideration  of  circumstances  be- 
longs to  the  orator.  But  oratory  is  not  a  part  of  theology. 
Therefore  it  is  not  a  theologian's  business  to  consider  cir- 
cumstances. 

On  the  contrary,  Ignorance  of  circumstances  causes  an  act 
to  be  involuntary,  according  to  Damascene  (De  Fide  Orthod. 
ii.)  and  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat.  Horn.  xxxi.). 
But  involuntariness  excuses  from  sin,  the  consideration  of 
which  iDelongs  to  the  theologian.  Therefore  circumstances 
also  should  be  considered  by  the  theologian. 

I  answer  that,  Circumstances  come  under  the  considera- 
tion of  the  theologian,  for  a  threefold  reason.  First,  because 
the  theologian  considers  human  acts,  inasmuch  as  man  is 
thereby  directed  to  Happiness.  Now,  everything  that  is 
directed  to  an  end  should  be  proportionate  to  that  end. 
But  acts  are  made  proportionate  to  an  end  by  means  of  a 
certain  commensurateness,  which  results  from  the  due  cir- 
cumstances. Hence  the  theologian  has  to  consider  the  cir- 
cumstances.— Secondly,  because  the  theologian  considers 
human  acts  according  as  they  are  found  to  be  good  or 
evil,  better  or  worse:  and  this  diversity  depends  on  circum- 
stances, as  we  shall  see  further  on  (Q.  XVIII.,  AA.  10,  11; 
Q.  LXXIIL,  A.  7). — Thirdly,  because  the  theologian  con- 
siders human  acts  under  the  aspect  of  merit  and  demerit, 
which  is  proper  to  human  acts;  and  for  this  it  is  requisite 
that  they  be  voluntary.  Now  a  human  act  is  deemed  to  be 
voluntary  or  involuntary,  according  to  knowledge  or  ignor- 
ance of  circumstances,  as  stated  above  {cf.  Q.  VI.,  A.  8). 
Therefore  the  theologian  has  to  consider  circumstances. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Good  directed  to  the  end  is  said  to  be  useful ; 
and  this  implies  some  kind  of  relation:  wherefore  the  Philo- 
sopher says  {Ethic,  i.)  that  good  in  relation  to  somethi^ig,  is 


io8  QUESTION  VII 

useful.  Now,  in  the  genus  relation  a  thing  is  denominated 
not  only  according  to  that  which  is  inherent  in  the  thing, 
but  also  according  to  that  which  is  extrinsic  to  it :  as  may 
be  seen  in  the  expressions  right  and  left,  equal  and  unequal, 
and  suchlike.  Accordingly,  since  the  goodness  of  acts 
consists  in  their  utility  to  the  end,  nothing  hinders  their 
being  called  good  or  bad  according  to  their  proportion  to 
extrinsic  things  that  are  adjacent  to  them. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Accidents  which  are  altogether  accidental 
are  neglected  by  every  art,  by  reason  of  their  uncertainty 
and  infinity.  But  suchlike  accidents  cannot  be  considered 
in  the  light  of  circumstances;  because  circumstances, 
although,  as  stated  above  (A.  i),  they  are  extrinsic  to  the 
act,  nevertheless  are  in  a  kind  of  contact  with  it,  by  being 
related  to  it.  Proper  accidents,  however,  come  under  the 
consideration  of  art. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  consideration  of  circumstances  belongs 
to  the  moralist,  the  politician,  and  the  orator.  To  the 
moralist,  in  so  far  as  with  respect  to  circumstances  we  find 
or  lose  the  mean  of  virtue  in  human  acts  and  passions.  To 
the  politician  and  to  the  orator,  in  so  far  as  circumstances 
make  acts  to  be  worthy  of  praise  or  blame,  of  excuse  or 
indictment.  In  different  ways,  however:  because  where  the 
orator  persuades,  the  politician  judges.  To  the  theologian 
this  consideration  belongs,  in  all  the  aforesaid  ways:  since 
to  him  all  the  other  acts  are  subservient :  for  he  has  to  con- 
sider virtuous  and  vicious  acts,  just  as  the  moralist  does; 
and  with  the  orator  and  politician  he  considers  acts  accord- 
ing as  they  are  deserving  of  reward  or  punishment. 

Third  Article. 

whether  the  circumstances  are  properly  set  forth 
in  the  third  book  of  ethics  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  circumstances  are  not 
properly  set  forth  in  Ethic,  iii.  For  a  circumstance  of  an 
act  is  described  as  something  outside  the  act.     Now  time 


CIRCUMSTANCES  OF  HUMAN  ACTS  109 

and  place  answer  to  this  description.  Therefore  there  are 
only  two  circumstances,  to  wit,  when  and  where. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  we  judge  from  the  circumstances  whether 
a  thing  is  well  or  ill  done.  But  this  belongs  to  the  mode  of 
an  act.  Therefore  all  the  circumstances  are  included  under 
one,  which  is  the  mode  of  acting. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  circumstances  are  not  part  of  the  sub- 
stance of  an  act.  But  the  causes  of  an  act  seem  to  belong 
to  its  substance.  Therefore  no  circumstance  should  be 
taken  from  the  cause  of  the  act  itself.  Accordingly,  neither 
who,  nor  why,  nor  about  what,  are  circumstances:  since  who 
refers  to  the  efficient  cause,  why  to  the  final  cause,  and 
about  what  to  the  material  cause. 

On  the  contrary  is  the  authority  of  the  Philosopher  in 
Ethic,  iii. 

/  answer  that,  Tully,  in  his  Rhetoric  (De  Invent.  Rhetor,  i.), 
gives  seven  circumstances,  which  are  contained  in  this 
verse : 

Quis,  quid,  uhi,  quihus  auxiliis,  cur,  quomodo,  quando — 
Who,  what,  where,  by  what  aids,  why,  how,  and  when. 

For  in  acts  we  must  take  note  of  who  did  it,  by  what  aids  or 
instruments  he  did  it,  what  he  did,  where  he  did  it,  why  he 
did  it,  how  and  when  he  did  it.  But  Aristotle  in  Ethic,  iii. 
added  yet  another,  to  wit,  about  what,  which  Tully  included 
in  the  circumstance  what. 

The  reason  of  this  enumeration  may  be  set  down  as 
follows.  For  a  circumstance  is  described  as  something  out- 
side the  substance  of  the  act,  and  yet  in  a  way  touching  it. 
Now  this  happens  in  three  ways :  first,  inasmuch  as  it  touches 
the  act  itself;  secondly,  inasmuch  as  it  touches  the  cause  of 
the  act;  thirdly,  inasmuch  as  it  touches  the  effect.  It 
touches  the  act  itself,  either  by  way  of  measure,  as  time  and 
place  ;  or  by  qualifying  the  act,  as  the  mode  of  acting.  It 
touches  the  effect,  when  we  consider  what  is  done.  It 
touches  the  cause  of  the  act,  as  to  the  final  cause,  by  the 
circumstance  why  ;  as  to  the  material  cause,  or  object,  in 
the  circumstance  about  what ;  as  to  the  principal  efficient 


no  QUESTION  VII 

cause,  in  the  circumstance  who  ;  and  as  to  the  instrumental 
efficient  cause,  in  the  circumstance  hy  what  aids. 

Reply  Oh],  i.  Time  and  place  surround  (circumstant)  the 
act  by  way  of  measure;  but  the  others  surround  the  act  by 
touching  it  in  any  other  way,  while  they  are  extrinsic  to  the 
substance  of  the  act. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  mode  well  or  ill  is  not  a  circumstance, 
but  results  from  all  the  circumstances.  But  the  mode  which 
refers  to  a  quality  of  the  act  is  a  special  circumstance;  for 
instance,  that  a  man  walk  fast  or  slowly;  that  he  strike 
hard  or  gently,  and  so  forth. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  A  condition  of  the  cause,  on  which  the  sub- 
stance of  the  act  depends,  is  not  a  circumstance;  it  must  be 
an  additional  condition.  Thus,  in  regard  to  the  object,  it 
is  not  a  circumstance  of  theft  that  the  object  is  another's 
property,  for  this  belongs  to  the  substance  of  the  act;  but 
that  it  be  great  or  small.  And  the  same  applies  to  the 
other  circumstances  which  are  considered  in  reference  to  the 
other  causes.  For  the  end  that  specifies  the  act  is  not  a 
circumstance,  but  some  additional  end.  Thus,  that  a 
valiant  man  act  valiantly  for  the  sake  of  the  good  of  the 
virtue  of  fortitude,  is  not  a  circumstance;  but  if  he  act 
valiantly  for  the  sake  of  the  delivery  of  the  state,  or  of 
Christendom,  or  some  such  purpose.  The  same  is  to  be 
said  with  regard  to  the  circumstance  what :  for  that  a  man 
by  pouring  water  on  someone  should  happen  to  wash  him, 
is  not  a  circumstance  of  the  washing;  but  that  in  doing  so 
he  give  him  a  chill,  or  scald  him;  heal  him  or  harm  him, 
these  are  circumstances. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  the  most  important  circumstances  are 

"why"    and   IN    "what   THE   ACT   CONSISTS"? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  these  are  not  the  most  im- 
portant circumstances,  namely,  why  and  those  in  which  the 
act  is  (iv  069  rj  irpd^t^),  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iii.     For  those  in 


CIRCUMSTANCES  OF  HUMAN  ACTS  iii 

which  the  act  is  seem  to  be  place  and  time :  and  these  do 
not  seem  to  be  the  most  important  of  the  circumstances, 
since,  of  them  all,  they  are  the  most  extrinsic  to  the  act. 
Therefore  those  things  in  which  the  act  is  are  not  the  most 
important  circumstances. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  end  of  a  thing  is  extrinsic  to  it. 
Therefore  it  is  not  the  most  important  circumstance. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  that  which  holds  the  foremost  place  in 
regard  to  each  thing,  is  its  cause  and  its  form.  But  the 
cause  of  an  act  is  the  person  that  does  it;  while  the  form  of 
an  act  is  the  manner  in  which  it  is  done.  Therefore 
these  two  circumstances  seem  to  be  of  the  greatest 
importance. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat. 
Horn,  xxxi.)  says  that  the  most  important  circumstances  are 
why  it  is  done  and  what  is  done. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  L,  A.  i),  acts  are 
properly  called  human,  inasmuch  as  they  are  voluntary. 
Now,  the  motive  and  object  of  the  will  is  the  end.  Therefore 
that  circumstance  is  the  most  important  of  all  which  touches 
the  act  on  the  part  of  the  end,  viz.,  the  circumstance  why  : 
and  the  second  in  importance,  is  that  which  touches  the 
very  substance  of  the  act,  viz.,  the  circumstance  what  he 
did.  As  to  the  other  circumstances,  they  are  more  or  less 
important,  according  as  they  more  or  less  approach  to 
these. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  By  those  things  in  which  the  act  is  the 
Philosopher  does  not  mean  time  and  place,  but  those  cir- 
cumstances that  are  affixed  to  the  act  itself.  Wherefore 
Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — loc.  cit.),  as  though  he  were 
explaining  the  dictum  of  the  Philosopher,  instead  of  the 
latter's  term, — in  which  the  act  is,  said,  what  is  done. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Although  the  end  is  not  part  of  the  sub- 
stance of  the  act,  yet  it  is  the  most  important  cause  of  the 
act,  inasmuch  as  it  moves  the  agent  to  act.  Wherefore  the 
moral  act  is  specified  chiefly  by  the  end. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  person  that  does  the  act  is  the  cause 
of  that  act,  inasmuch  as  he  is  moved  thereto  by  the  end; 


112  QUESTION  VII 

and  it  is  chiefly  in  this  respect  that  he  is  directed  to  the 
act;  while  other  conditions  of  the  person  have  not  such  an 
important  relation  to  the  act. — ^As  to  the  mode,  it  is  not 
the  substantial  form  of  the  act,  for  in  an  act  the  substantial 
form  depends  on  the  object  and  term  or  end;  but  it  is,  as 
it  were,  a  certain  accidental  quality  of  the  act. 


QUESTION  VIII. 

OF  THE  WILL,  IN  REGARD  TO  WHAT  IT  WILLS. 

{In  Three  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  different  acts  of  the  will;  and 
in  the  first  place,  those  acts  which  belong  to  the  will  itself 
immediately,  as  being  elicited  by  the  will;  secondly,  those 
acts  which  are  commanded  by  the  will. 

Now  the  will  is  moved  to  the  end,  and  to  the  means  to 
the  end;  we  must  therefore  consider — (i)  Those  acts  of  the 
will  whereby  it  is  moved  to  the  end;  and  (2)  those  whereby 
it  is  moved  to  the  means.  And  since  it  seems  that  there 
are  three  acts  of  the  will  in  reference  to  the  end;  viz.,  voli- 
tion, enjoyment,  and  intention  ;  we  must  consider — (i)  Voli- 
tion; (2)  enjoyment;  (3)  intention. — Concerning  the  first, 
three  things  must  be  considered:  (i)  Of  what  things  is  the 
will  ?  (2)  By  what  is  the  will  moved  ?  (3)  How  is  it 
moved  ? 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  three  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  the  will  is  of  good  only  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  of 
the  end  only,  or  also  of  the  means  ?  (3)  If  in  any  way  it 
be  of  the  means,  whether  it  be  moved  to  the  end  and  to  the 
means,  by  the  same  movement  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  the  will  is  of  good  only  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  not  of  good  only. 
For  the  same  power  regards  opposites;  for  instance, 
sight   regards   white   and  black.     But  good   and   evil   are 

II.  I  113  8 


114  QUESTION  VIII 

opposites.  Therefore  the  will  is  not  only  of  good,  but  also 
of  evil. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  rational  powers  can  be  directed  to  oppo- 
site purposes,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Metaph.  viii.). 
But  the  will  is  a  rational  power,  since  it  is  in  the  reason,  as 
is  stated  in  De  Anima  iii.  Therefore  the  will  can  be  directed 
to  opposites;  and  consequently  its  volition  is  not  confined 
to  good,  but  extends  to  evil. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  good  and  being  are  convertible.  But 
volition  is  directed  not  only  to  beings,  but  also  to  non- 
beings.  For  sometimes  we  wish  not  to  walk,  or  not  to  speak  ; 
and  again  at  times  we  wish  for  future  things,  which  are  not 
actual  beings.     Therefore  the  will  is  not  of  good  only. 

On  the  contrary,  Dionysius  says  [Div.  Nom.  iv.)  that  evil 
is  outside  the  scope  of  the  will,  and  that  all  things  desire  good. 

I  answer  that,  The  will  is  a  rational  appetite.  Now 
every  appetite  is  only  of  something  good.  The  reason  of 
this  is  that  the  appetite  is  nothing  else  than  an  inclination 
of  a  person  desirous  of  a  thing  towards  that  thing.  Now 
every  inclination  is  to  something  like  and  suitable  to  the 
thing  inclined.  Since,  therefore,  everything,  inasmuch  as 
it  is  being  and  substance,  is  a  good,  it  must  needs  be  that 
every  inclination  is  to  something  good.  And  hence  it  is 
that  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  i.)  that  the  good  is  that 
which  all  desire. 

But  it  must  be  noted  that,  since  every  inclination  results 
from  a  form,  the  natural  appetite  results  from  a  form 
existing  in  the  nature  of  things :  while  the  sensitive  appetite, 
as  also  the  intellective  or  rational  appetite,  which  we  call 
the  will,  follows  from  an  apprehended  form.  Therefore, 
just  as  the  natural  appetite  tends  to  good  existing  in  a 
thing;  so  the  animal  or  voluntary  appetite  tends  to  a  good 
which  is  apprehended.  Consequently,  in  order  that  the  will 
tend  to  anything,  it  is  requisite,  not  that  this  be  good  in 
very  truth,  but  that  it  be  apprehended  as  good.  Wherefore 
the  Philosopher  says  {Phys.  ii.)  that  the  end  is  a  good,  or  an 
apparent  good. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  same  power  regards  opposites,  but  it  is 


THE  OBJECT  OF  VOLITION  115 

not  referred  to  them  in  the  same  way.  Accordingly,  the 
will  is  referred  both  to  good  and  to  evil:  but  to  good,  Ly 
desiring  it:  to  evil,  by  shunning  it.  Wherefore  the  actual 
desire  of  good  is  called  volition,'^  meaning  thereby  the  act 
of  the  will;  for  it  is  in  this  sense  that  we  are  now  speaking 
of  the  will.  On  the  other  hand,  the  shunning  of  evil  is 
better  described  as  nolition  :  wherefore,  just  as  volition  is  of 
good,  so  nolition  is  of  evil. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  A  rational  power  is  not  to  be  directed  to 
any  opposite  purposes,  but  to  those  which  are  contained 
under  its  proper  object:  for  no  power  seeks  other  than  its 
proper  object.  Now,  the  object  of  the  will  is  good.  Where- 
fore the  will  can  be  directed  to  such  opposite  purposes  as  are 
contained  under  good,  such  as  to  be  moved,  or  to  be  at  rest, 
to  speak  or  to  be  silent,  and  suchlike:  for  the  will  can  be 
directed  to  either  under  the  aspect  of  good. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  That  which  is  not  a  being  in  nature^  is  con- 
sidered as  a  being  in  the  reason,  wherefore  negations  and 
privations  are  said  to  be  beings  of  reason.  In  this  way,  too, 
future  things,  in  so  far  as  they  are  apprehended,  are  beings. 
Accordingly,  in  so  far  as  suchlike  are  beings,  they  are  appre- 
hended under  the  aspect  of  good;  and  it  is  thus  that  the 
will  is  directed  to  them.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic.  V.)  that  to  lack  evil  is  considered  as  a  good. 

Second  Article, 
whether  volition  is  of  the  end  only,  or  also  of  the 

MEANS  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  volition  is  not  of  the  means, 
but  of  the  end  only.  For  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.) 
that  volition  is  of  the  end,  while  choice  is  of  the  means. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  For  objects  differing  in  genus  there  are 
corresponding  different  powers  of  the  soul  {Ethic,  vi.).     Now, 

*  In  Latin, — -voluntas.  To  avoid  confusion  with  voluntas  (the 
will)  St.  Thomas  adds  a  word  of  explanation,  which  in  the  transla- 
tion may  appear  superfluous. 


ii6  QUESTION  VIII 

the  end  and  the  means  are  in  different  genera  of  good: 
because  the  end,  which  is  a  good  either  of  rectitude  or  of 
pleasure,  is  in  the  genus  quality,  either  of  action  or  of  passion; 
whereas  the  good  which  is  useful,  and  is  directed  to  an  end, 
is  in  the  genus  relation  {Ethic,  i.).  Therefore,  if  volition  is 
of  the  end,  it  is  not  of  the  means. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  habits  are  proportionate  to  powers,  since 
they  are  perfections  thereof.  But  in  those  habits  which  are 
called  practical  arts,  the  end  belongs  to  one,  and  the  means 
to  another  art;  thus  the  use  of  a  ship,  which  is  its  end, 
belongs  to  the  (art  of  the)  helmsman;  whereas  the  building 
of  the  ship,  which  is  directed  to  the  end,  belongs  to  the  art 
of  the  shipwright.  Therefore,  since  volition  is  of  the  end, 
it  is  not  of  the  means. 

On  the  contrary,  In  natural  things,  it  is  by  the  same  power 
that  a  thing  passes  through  the  middle  space,  and  arrives 
at  the  terminus.  But  the  means  are  a  kind  of  middle  space, 
through  which  one  arrives  at  the  end  or  terminus.  There- 
fore, if  volition  is  of  the  end,  it  is  also  of  the  means. 

I  answer  that,  The  word  voluntas  sometimes  designates  the 
power  of  the  will,  sometimes  its  act.*  Accordingly,  if  we 
speak  of  the  will  as  a  power,  thus  it  extends  both  to  the 
end  and  to  the  means.  For  every  power  extends  to  those 
things  in  which  may  be  considered  the  aspect  of  the  object 
of  that  power  in  any  way  whatever :  thus  the  sight  extends 
to  all  things  whatsoever  that  are  in  any  way  coloured. 
Now  the  aspect  of  good,  which  is  the  object  of  the  will 
power,  may  be  found  not  only  in  the  end,  but  also  in  the 
means. 

If,  however,  we  speak  of  the  will  in  regard  to  its  act,  then, 
properly  speaking,  voHtion  is  of  the  end  only.  Because 
every  act  denominated  from  a  power,  designates  the  simple 
act  of  that  power:  thus  to  understand  designates  the  simple 
act  of  the  understanding.  Now  the  simple  act  of  a  power 
is  referred  to  that  which  is  in  itself  the  object  of  that  power. 
But  that  which  is  good  and  willed  in  itself  is  the  end.  Where- 
fore volition,  properly  speaking,  is  of  the  end  itself.     On  the 

*  See  note  on  p.  115. 


THE  OBJECT  OF  VOLITION  117 

other  hand,  the  means  are  good  and  willed,  not  in  them- 
selves, but  as  referred  to  the  end.  Wherefore  the  will  is 
directed  to  them,  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  directed  to  the  end : 
so  that  what  it  wills  in  them,  is  the  end.  Thus,  to  under- 
stand, is  properly  directed  to  things  that  are  known  in 
themselves,  i.e.,  first  principles:  but  we  do  not  speak  of 
understanding  with  regard  to  things  known  through  first 
principles,  except  in  so  far  as  we  see  the  principles  in 
those  things.  For  in  morals  the  end  is  what  principles  are 
in  speculative  science  {cf.  Ethic,  vii.). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  Philosopher  is  speaking  of  the  will  in 
reference  to  the  simple  act  of  the  will;  not  in  reference  to 
the  power  of  the  will. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  There  are  different  powers  for  objects  that 
differ  in  genus  in  an  equal  degree;  for  instance,  sound  and 
colour  are  different  genera  of  sensibles,  to  which  are  referred 
hearing  and  sight.  But  the  useful  and  the  righteous  are 
mutually  related  not  in  an  equal  degree,  but  as  that  which  is 
of  itself,  and  that  which  is  in  relation  to  another.  Now 
suchlike  objects  are  always  referred  to  the  same  power;  for 
instance,  the  power  of  sight  perceives  both  colour  and  light 
by  which  colour  is  seen. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Not  everything  that  diversifies  habits, 
diversifies  the  powers:  since  habits  are  certain  determina- 
tions of  powers  to  certain  special  acts.  Moreover,  every 
practical  art  considers  both  the  end  and  the  means.  For  the 
art  of  the  helmsman  does  indeed  consider  the  end,  as  that 
which  it  effects;  and  the  means,  as  that  which  it  commands. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  ship-building  art  considers  the  means 
as  that  which  it  effects;  but  it  considers  that  which  is  the 
end,  as  that  to  which  it  refers  what  it  effects.  And  again, 
in  every  practical  art  there  is  an  end  proper  to  it,  and  means 
that  belong  properly  to  that  art. 


ii8  QUESTION  VIII 


Third  Article. 

whether  the  will  is  moved  by  the  same  act  to  the  end 

and  to  the  means  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  moved  by  the  same 
act,  to  the  end  and  to  the  means.  Because  according  to 
the  Philosopher  {Topic,  iii.)  where  one  thing  is  on  account  of 
another  there  is  only  one.  But  the  will  does  not  will  the 
means  save  on  account  of  the  end.  Therefore  it  is  moved 
to  both  by  the  same  act. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  end  is  the  reason  for  willing  the  means, 
just  as  light  is  the  reason  of  seeing  colours.  But  light  and 
colours  are  seen  by  the  same  act.  Therefore  it  is  the  same 
movement  of  the  will,  whereby  it  wills  the  end  and  the 
means. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  it  is  one  and  the  same  natural  movement 
which  tends  through  the  middle  space  to  the  terminus. 
But  the  means  are  in  comparison  to  the  end,  as  the  middle 
space  is  to  the  terminus.  Therefore  it  is  the  same  move- 
ment of  the  will  whereby  it  is  directed  to  the  end  and  to  the 
means. 

On  the  contrary,  Acts  are  diversified  according  to  their 
objects.  But  the  end  is  a  different  species  of  good  from  the 
means,  which  are  a  useful  good.  Therefore  the  will  is  not 
moved  to  both  by  the  same  act. 

I  answer  that,  Since  the  end  is  willed  in  itself,  whereas  the 
means,  as  such,  are  only  willed  for  the  end,  it  is  evident  that 
the  will  can  be  moved  to  the  end,  without  being  moved  to 
the  means ;  whereas  it  cannot  be  moved  to  the  means,  as 
such,  unless  it  is  moved  to  the  end.  Accordingly  the  will 
is  moved  to  the  end  in  two  ways :  first,  to  the  end  absolutely 
and  in  itself;  secondly,  as  to  the  reason  for  willing  the  means. 
Hence  it  is  evident  that  the  will  is  moved  by  one  and  the 
same  movement, — ^to  the  end,  as  the  reason  for  willing  the 
means, — and  to  the  means  themselves.  But  it  is  another 
act  whereby  the  will  is  moved  to  the  end  absolutely.     And 


THE  OBJECT  OF  VOLITION  119 

sometimes  this  act  precedes  the  other  in  time;  for  example, 
when  a  man  first  wills  to  have  health,  and  afterwards, 
deliberating  by  what  means  to  be  healed,  wills  to  send  for 
the  doctor  to  heal  him.  The  same  happens  in  regard  to  the 
intellect:  for  at  first  a  man  understands  the  principles  in 
themselves;  but  afterwards  he  understands  them  in  the 
conclusions,  inasmuch  as  he  assents  to  the  conclusions  on 
account  of  the  principles. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  argument  holds  in  respect  of  the  will 
being  moved  to  the  end  as  the  reason  for  willing  the  means. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Whenever  colour  is  seen,  by  the  same  act 
the  light  is  seen;  but  the  light  can  be  seen  without  the  colour 
being  seen.  In  like  manner  whenever  a  man  wills  the 
means,  by  the  same  act  he  wills  the  end;  but  not  conversely. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  In  the  execution  of  a  work,  the  means  are 
as  the  middle- space,  and  the  end,  as  the  terminus.  Where- 
fore just  as  natural  movement  sometimes  stops  in  the 
middle  and  does  not  reach  the  terminus;  so  sometimes  one 
is  busy  with  the  means,  without  gaining  the  end.  But  in 
willing  it  is  the  reverse:  for  the  will  through  (willing)  the 
end  comes  to  will  the  means;  just  as  the  intellect  arrives  at 
the  conclusions  through  the  principles  which  are  called 
means.  Hence  it  is  that  sometimes  the  intellect  under- 
stands a  mean,  and  does  not  proceed  thence  to  the  conclusion. 
And  in  like  manner  the  will  sometimes  wills  the  end,  and  yet 
does  not  proceed  to  will  the  means. 

The  solution  to  the  argument  in  the  contrary  sense  is 
clear  from  what  has  been  said  above  (A.  2  ad  2).  For  the 
useful  and  the  righteous  are  not  species  of  good  in  an  equal 
degree,  but  are  as  that  which  is  for  its  own  sake  and  that 
which  is  for  the  sake  of  something  else :  wherefore  the  act 
of  the  will  can  be  directed  to  one  and  not  to  the  other;  but 
not  conversely. 


QUESTION  IX. 

OF  THAT  WHICH  MOVES  THE  WILL. 

{In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  what  moves  the  will :  and  under  this 
head  there  are  six  points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether  the  will  is 
moved  by  the  intellect  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  moved  by  the 
sensitive  appetite  ?     (3)   Whether  the  will  moves  itself  ? 

(4)  Whether    it    is    moved    by    an    extrinsic    principle  ? 

(5)  Whether  it  is  moved  by  a  heavenly  body  ?  (6)  Whether 
the  will  is  moved  by  God  alone  as  by  an  extrinsic  principle  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  the  will  is  moved  by  the  intellect  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  not  moved  by  the 
intellect.  For  Augustine  says  on  Ps.  cxviii.  20:  My  soul 
hath  coveted  to  long  for  Thy  justifications  : — The  intellect  flies 
ahead,  the  desire  follows  sluggishly  or  not  at  all :  we  know  what 
is  good,  hut  deeds  delight  us  not.  But  it  would  not  be  so,  if 
the  intellect  were  moved  by  the  will :  because  movement  of 
the  movable  results  from  motion  of  the  mover.  Therefore 
the  intellect  does  not  move  the  will. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  intellect  in  presenting  the  appetible 
object  to  the  will,  stands  in  relation  to  the  will,  as  the  imagina- 
tion in  representing  the  appetible  object  to  the  sensitive 
appetite.  But  the  imagination,  in  presenting  the  appetible 
object,  does  not  move  the  sensitive  appetite:  indeed,  some- 
times our  imagination  affects  us  no  more  than  what  is  set 

120 


WHAT  MOVES  THE  WILL  121 

before  us  in  a  picture,  and  moves  us  not  at  all  {De  Anima,  iii.) . 
Therefore  neither  does  the  intellect  move  the  will. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  same  is  not  mover  and  moved  in 
respect  of  the  same  thing.  But  the  will  moves  the  in- 
tellect; for  we  exercise  the  intellect  when  we  will.  There- 
fore the  intellect  does  not  move  the  will. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  [De  Anima  iii.)  that 
the  appetihle  object  is  a  mover  not  moved,  whereas  the  will  is 
a  mover  moved. 

I  answer  that,  A  thing  requires  to  be  moved  by  something 
in  so  far  as  it  is  in  potentiality  to  several  things;  for  that 
which  is  in  potentiality  needs  to  be  reduced  to  act  by  some- 
thing actual;  and  to  do  this  is  to  move.  Now  a  power  of 
the  soul  is  seen  to  be  in  potentiality  to  different  things  in 
two  ways :  first,  with  regard  to  acting  and  not  acting ; 
secondly,  with  regard  to  this  or  that  action.  Thus  the 
sight  sometimes  sees  actually,  and  sometimes  sees  not:  and 
sometimes  it  sees  white,  and  sometimes  black.  It  needs 
therefore  a  mover  in  two  respects:  viz.,  as  to  the  exercise 
or  use  of  the  act,  and  as  to  the  determination  of  the  act. 
The  first  of  these  is  on  the  part  of  the  subject,  which  is 
sometimes  acting,  sometimes  not  acting:  while  the  other  is 
on  the  part  of  the  object,  by  reason  of  which  the  act  is 
specified. 

The  motion  of  the  subject  itself  is  due  to  some  agent. 
And  since  every  agent  acts  for  an  end,  as  was  shown  above 
(Q.  I.,  A.  2),  the  principle  of  this  motion  lies  in  the  end. 
And  hence  it  is  that  the  art  which  is  concerned  with  the  end, 
by  its  command  moves  the  art  which  is  concerned  with  the 
means:  just  as  the  art  of  sailing  commands  the  art  of  ship- 
building (Phys.  ii.).  Now  good  in  general,  which  has  the 
nature  of  an  end,  is  the  object  of  the  will.  Consequently, 
in  this  respect,  the  will  moves  the  other  powers  of  the  soul 
to  their  acts :  for  we  make  use  of  the  other  powers  when  we 
will.  For  the  end  and  perfection  of  every  other  power,  is 
included  under  the  object  of  the  will  as  some  particular 
good:  and  always  the  act  or  power  to  which  the  universal 
end  belongs,  moves  to  their  acts  the  acts  or  powers  to  which 


122  QUESTION  IX 

belong  the  particular  ends  included  in  that  universal  end. 
Thus  the  leader  of  an  army,  who  intends  the  common  good — 
i.e.,  the  order  of  the  whole  army — by  his  command  moves 
one  of  the  captains,  who  intends  the  order  of  one  company. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  object  moves,  by  determining  the 
act,  after  the  manner  of  a  formal  principle,  whereby  in 
natural  things  actions  are  specified,  as  heating  by  heat. 
Now  the  first  formal  principle  is  universal  being  and  truth, 
which  is  the  object  of  the  intellect.  And  therefore  by  this 
kind  of  motion  the  intellect  moves  the  will,  as  presenting  its 
object  to  it. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  passage  quoted  proves,  not  that  the 
intellect  does  not  move,  but  that  it  does  not  move  of 
necessity. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Just  as  the  imagination  of  a  form  without 
estimation  of  fitness  or  harmfulness,  does  not  move  the 
sensitive  appetite;  so  neither  does  the  apprehension  of  the 
true  without  the  aspect  of  goodness  and  desirability.  Hence 
it  is  not  the  speculative  intellect  that  moves,  but  the  prac- 
tical intellect  {De  Anima  iii.). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  will  moves  the  intellect  as  to  the  exer- 
cise of  its  act;  since  even  the  true  itself  which  is  the  per- 
fection of  the  intellect,  is  included  in  the  universal  good, 
as  a  particular  good.  But  as  to  the  determination  of  the 
act,  which  the  act  derives  from  the  object,  the  intellect 
moves  the  will;  since  the  good  itself  is  apprehended  under 
a  special  aspect  as  contained  in  the  universal  true.  It  is 
therefore  evident  that  the  same  is  not  mover  and  moved 
in  the  same  respect. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  will  is  moved  by  the  sensitive 

appetite  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  cannot  be  moved  by 
the  sensitive  appetite.  For  to  move  and  to  act  is  more  ex- 
cellent than  to  he  passive,  as  Augustine  says  {Gen.  ad  lit.  xii.). 


WHAT  MOVES  THE  WILL  123 

But  the  sensitive  appetite  is  less  excellent  than  the  will 
which  is  the  intellectual  appetite;  just  as  sense  is  less  ex- 
cellent than  intellect.  Therefore  the  sensitive  appetite 
does  not  move  the  will. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  no  particular  power  can  produce  a  uni- 
versal effect.  But  the  sensitive  appetite  is  a  particular 
power,  because  it  follows  the  particular  apprehension  of 
sense.  Therefore  it  cannot  cause  the  movement  of  the  will, 
which  movement  is  universal,  as  following  the  universal 
apprehension  of  the  intellect. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  as  is  proved  in  Phys.  viii.,  the  mover  is 
not  moved  by  that  which  it  moves,  in  such  a  way  that  there 
be  reciprocal  motion.  But  the  will  moves  the  sensitive 
appetite,  inasmuch  as  the  sensitive  appetite  obeys  the 
reason.  Therefore  the  sensitive  appetite  does  not  move 
the  will. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (James  i.  14) :  Every  man  is 
tempted  by  his  own  concupiscence,  being  drawn  away  and 
allured.  But  man  would  not  be  drawn  away  by  his  con- 
cupiscence, unless  his  will  were  moved  by  the  sensitive 
appetite,  wherein  concupiscence  resides.  Therefore  the 
sensitive  appetite  moves  the  will. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  that  which  is  appre- 
hended as  good  and  fitting,  moves  the  will  by  way  of  object. 
Now,  that  a  thing  appear  to  be  good  and  fitting,  happens 
from  two  causes :  namely,  from  the  condition,  either  of  the 
thing  proposed,  or  of  the  one  to  whom  it  is  proposed.  But 
fitness  is  spoken  of  by  way  of  relation;  hence  it  depends  on 
both  extremes.  And  hence  it  is  that  taste,  according  as 
it  is  variously  disposed,  takes  to  a  thing  in  various  ways, 
as  being  fitting  or  unfitting.  Wherefore  as  the  Philoso- 
pher says  {Ethic,  iii.) :  According  as  a  man  is,  such  does  the 
end  seem  to  him. 

Now  it  is  evident  that  according  to  the  sensitive  appetite 
man  is  changed  to  a  certain  disposition.  Wherefore  accord- 
ing as  man  is  affected  by  a  passion,  something  seems  to  him 
fitting,  which  does  not  seem  so  when  he  is  not  so  affected : 
thus  that  seems  good  to  a  man  when  angered,  which  does 


124  QUESTION  IX 

not  seem  good  when  he  is  calm.  And  in  this  way,  the  sensi- 
tive appetite  moves  the  will,  on  the  part  of  the  object. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Nothing  hinders  that  which  is  better  simply 
and  in  itself,  from  being  less  excellent  in  a  certain  respect. 
Accordingly  the  will  is  simply  more  excellent  than  the 
sensitive  appetite:  but  in  respect  of  the  man  in  whom  a 
passion  is  predominant,  in  so  far  as  he  is  subject  to  that 
passion,  the  sensitive  appetite  is  more  excellent. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Men's  acts  and  choices  are  in  reference  to 
singulars.  Wherefore  from  the  very  fact  that  the  sensitive 
appetite  is  a  particular  power,  it  has  great  influence  in 
disposing  man  so  that  something  seems  to  him  such  or  other- 
wise, in  particular  cases. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Polit.  i.),  the  reason, 
in  which  resides  the  will,  moves,  by  its  command,  the 
irascible  and  concupiscible  powers,  not,  indeed,  hy  a  despotic 
sovereignty,  as  a  slave  is  moved  by  his  master,  but  by  a  royal 
and  politic  sovereignty,  as  free  men  are  ruled  by  their  gover- 
nor, and  can  nevertheless  act  counter  to  his  commands. 
Hence  both  irascible  and  concupiscible  can  move  counter  to 
the  will :  and  accordingly  nothing  hinders  the  will  from  being 
moved  by  them  at  times. 

Third  Article, 
whether  the  will  moves  itself  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  does  not  move  itself. 
For  every  mover,  as  such,  is  in  act :  whereas  what  is  moved, 
is  in  potentiality ;  since  movement  is  the  act  of  that  which  is  in 
potentiality,  as  such  (Aristotle, — -Phys.  iii.).  Now  the  same 
is  not  in  potentiality  and  in  act,  in  respect  of  the  same. 
Therefore  nothing  moves  itself.  Neither,  therefore,  can  the 
will  move  itself. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  movable  is  moved  on  the  mover  being 
present.  But  the  will  is  always  present  to  itself.  If,  there- 
fore, it  moved  itself,  it  would  always  be  moving  itself:  which 
is  clearly  false. 


WHAT  MOVES  THE  WILL  125 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  will  is  moved  by  the  intellect,  as 
stated  above  (A.  i).  If,  therefore,  the  will  move  itself,  it 
would  follow  that  the  same  thing  is  at  once  moved  imme- 
diately by  two  movers;  which  seems  unreasonable.  There- 
fore the  will  does  not  move  itself. 

On  the  contrary,  The  will  is  mistress  of  its  own  act,  and  to 
it  belongs  to  will  and  not  to  will.  But  this  would  not  be 
so,  had  it  not  the  power  to  move  itself  to  will.  Therefore  it 
moves  itself. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  it  belongs  to  the  will 
to  move  the  other  powers,  by  reason  of  the  end  which  is  the 
will's  object.  Now,  as  stated  above  (Q.  VIIL,  A.  2),  the 
end  is  in  things  appetible,  what  the  principle  is  in  things 
intelligible.  But  it  is  evident  that  the  intellect,  through 
its  knowledge  of  the  principle,  reduces  itself  from  poten- 
tiality to  act,  as  to  its  knowledge  of  the  conclusions;  and 
thus  it  moves  itself.  And,  in  like  manner,  the  will,  through 
its  volition  of  the  end,  moves  itself  to  will  the  means. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  It  is  not  in  respect  of  the  same  that  the  will 
moves  itself  and  is  moved:  wherefore  neither  is  it  in  act  and 
in  potentiality  in  respect  of  the  same.  But  forasmuch  as  it 
actually  wills  the  end,  it  reduces  itself  from  potentiality  to 
act,  in  respect  of  the  means;  so  as,  in  a  word,  to  will  them 
actually. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  power  of  the  will  is  always  actually 
present  to  itself;  but  the  act  of  the  will,  whereby  it  wills 
an  end,  is  not  always  in  the  will.  And  to  this  purpose  it 
moves  itself.  Accordingly  it  does  not  follow  that  it  is 
always  moving  itself. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  will  is  moved  by  the  intellect,  otherwise 
than  by  itself.  By  the  intellect  it  is  moved  on  the  part  of 
the  object:  whereas  it  is  moved  by  itself,  as  to  the  exercise 
of  its  act,  in  respect  of  the  end. 


126  QUESTION  IX 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  will  is  moved  by  an  exterior 

principle  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  not  moved  by  any- 
thing exterior.  For  the  movement  of  the  will  is  voluntary. 
But  it  is  essential  to  the  voluntary  act  that  it  be  from  an 
intrinsic  principle,  just  as  it  is  essential  to  the  natural  act. 
Therefore  the  movement  of  the  will  is  not  from  anything 
exterior. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  will  cannot  suffer  violence,  as  was 
shown  above  (Q.  VI.,  A.  4).  But  the  violent  act  is  one  the 
principle  of  which  is  outside  the  agent  (Aristotle, — Ethic,  iii.). 
Therefore  the  will  cannot  be  moved  by  anything  exterior. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  that  which  is  sufficiently  moved  by  one 
mover,  needs  not  to  be  moved  by  another.  But  the  will 
moves  itself  sufficiently.  Therefore  it  is  not  moved  by  any 
thing  exterior. 

On  the  contrary,  The  will  is  moved  by  the  object,  as  stated 
above  (A.  i).  But  the  object  of  the  will  can  be  something 
exterior,  offered  to  the  sense.  Therefore  the  will  can  be 
moved  by  something  exterior. 

/  answer  that,  As  far  as  the  will  is  moved  by  the  object,  it 
is  evident  that  it  can  be  moved  by  something  exterior.  But 
in  so  far  as  it  is  moved  in  the  exercise  of  its  act,  we  must 
again  hold  it  to  be  moved  by  some  exterior  principle. 

For  everything  that  is  at  one  time  an  agent  actually,  and 
at  another  time  an  agent  in  potentiality,  needs  to  be  moved 
by  a  mover.  Now  it  is  evident  that  the  will  begins  to  will 
something,  whereas  previously  it  did  not  will  it.  Therefore 
it  must,  of  necessity,  be  moved  by  something  to  will  it. 
And,  indeed,  it  moves  itself,  as  stated  above  (A.  3),  in  so  far 
as  through  willing  the  end  it  reduces  itself  to  the  act  of 
willing  the  means.  Now  it  cannot  do  this  without  the  aid 
of  counsel :  for  when  a  man  wills  to  be  healed,  he  begins  to 
reflect  how  this  can  be  attained,  and  through  this  reflexion 


WHAT  MOVES  THE  WILL  127 

he  comes  to  the  conclusion  that  he  can  be  healed  by  a 
physician:  and  this  he  wills.  But  since  he  did  not  always 
actually  will  to  have  health,  he  must,  of  necessity,  have 
begun,  through  something  moving  him,  to  will  to  be  healed. 
And  if  the  will  moved  itself  to  will  this,  it  must,  of  necessity 
have  done  this  with  the  aid  of  counsel  following  some  previous 
volition.  But  this  process  could  not  go  on  to  infinity. 
Wherefore  we  must,  of  necessity,  suppose  that  the  will 
advanced  to  its  first  movement  in  virtue  of  the  instigation 
of  some  exterior  mover,  as  Aristotle  concludes  in  a  chapter 
of  the  Eudemian  Ethics. (vii.  14). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  It  is  essential  to  the  voluntary  act  that  its 
principle  be  within  the  agent:  but  it  is  not  necessary  that 
this  inward  principle  be  the  first  principle  unmoved  by 
another.  Wherefore  though  the  voluntary  act  has  an  in- 
ward proximate  principle,  nevertheless  its  first  principle 
is  from  without.  Thus,  too,  the  first  principle  of  the 
natural  movement  is  from  without,  that,  to  wit,  which 
moves  nature. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  For  an  act  to  be  violent  it  is  not  enough 
that  its  principle  be  extrinsic,  but  we  must  add  without 
the  concurrence  of  him  that  suffers  violence.  This  does  not 
happen  when  the  will  is  moved  by  an  exterior  principle :  for 
it  is  the  will  that  wills,  though  moved  by  another.  But  this 
movement  would  be  violent,  if  it  were  counter  to  the  move- 
ment of  the  will:  which  in  the  present  case  is  impossible; 
since  then  the  will  would  will  and  not  will  the  same  thing. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  will  moves  itself  sufficiently  in  one 
respect,  and  in  its  own  order,  that  is  to  say  as  proximate 
agent ;  but  it  cannot  move  itself  in  every  respect,  as  we  have 
shown.  Wherefore  it  needs  to  be  moved  by  another  as 
first  mover. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  the  will  is  moved  by  a  heavenly  body  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 
Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  the  human  will  is  moved  by  a 
heavenly  body.     For  all  various  and  multiform  movements 


128  QUESTION  IX 

are  reduced,  as  to  their  cause,  to  a  uniform  movement  which 
is  that  of  the  heavens,  as  is  proved  in  Phys.  viii.  But  human 
movements  are  various  and  multiform,  since  they  begin  to 
be,  whereas  previously  they  were  not.  Therefore  they  are 
reduced,  as  to  their  cause,  to  the  movement  of  the  heavens, 
which  is  uniform  according  to  its  nature. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  according  to  Augustine  (De  Trin.  iii.) 
the  lower  bodies  are  moved  by  the  higher.  But  the  movements 
of  the  human  body,  which  are  caused  by  the  will,  could  not 
be  reduced  to  the  movement  of  the  heavens,  as  to  their 
cause,  unless  the  will  too  were  moved  by  the  heavens. 
Therefore  the  heavens  move  the  human  will. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  by  observing  the  heavenly  bodies 
astrologers  foretell  the  truth  about  future  human  acts, 
which  are  caused  by  the  will.  But  this  would  not  be  so,  if 
the  heavenly  bodies  could  not  move  man's  will.  Therefore 
the  human  will  is  moved  by  a  heavenly  body. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that 
the  heavenly  bodies  are  not  the  causes  of  our  acts.  But  they 
would  be,  if  the  will,  which  is  the  principle  of  human  acts, 
were  moved  by  the  heavenly  bodies.  Therefore  the  will  is 
not  moved  by  the  heavenly  bodies. 

I  answer  that,  It  is  evident  that  the  will  can  be  moved  by 
the  heavenly  bodies  in  the  same  way  as  it  is  moved  by  its 
object:  that  is  to  say,  in  so  far  as  exterior  bodies,  which 
move  the  will,  through  being  offered  to  the  senses,  and  also 
the  organs  themselves  of  the  sensitive  powers,  are  subject 
to  the  movements  of  the  heavenly  bodies. 

But  some  have  maintained  that  heavenly  bodies  have  an 
influence  on  the  human  will,  in  the  same  way  as  some  exterior 
agent  moves  the  will,  as  to  the  exercise  of  its  act. — But 
this  is  impossible.  For  the  will,  as  stated  in  De  Anima  iii., 
is  in  the  reason.  Now  the  reason  is  a  power  of  the  soul,  not 
bound  to  a  bodily  organ:  wherefore  it  follows  that  the  will 
is  a  power  absolutely  incorporeal  and  immaterial.  But  it  is 
evident  that  no  body  can  act  on  what  is  incorporeal,  but 
rather  the  reverse:  because  things  incorporeal  and  imma- 
terial have  a  power  more  formal  and  more  universal  than 


WHAT  MOVES  THE  WILL  129 

any  corporeal  things  whatever.  Therefore  it  is  impossible 
for  a  heavenly  body  to  act  directly  on  the  intellect  or  the 
will. — For  this  reason  Aristotle  (De  Anima  iii.)  ascribed  to 
those  who  held  that  intellect  differs  not  from  sense,  the 
theory  that  such  is  the  will  of  men,  as  is  the  day  which  the 
father  of  men  and  of  gods  brings  on*  (referring  to  Jupiter, 
by  whom  they  understand  the  entire  heavens).  For  all 
the  sensitive  powers,  since  they  are  acts  of  bodily  organs, 
can  be  moved  accidentally,  by  the  heavenly  bodies — i.e., 
through  those  bodies  being  moved,  whose  acts  they  are. 

But  since  it  has  been  stated  (A.  2)  that  the  intellectual 
appetite  is  moved,  in  a  fashion,  by  the  sensitive  appetite, 
the  movements  of  the  heavenly  bodies  have  an  indirect 
bearing  on  the  will ;  in  so  far  as  the  will  happens  to  be  moved 
by  the  passions  of  the  sensitive  appetite. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  multiform  movements  of  the  human  will 
are  reduced  to  some  uniform  cause,  which,  however,  is  above 
the  intellect  and  will.  This  can  be  said,  not  of  any  body, 
but  of  some  superior  immaterial  substance.  Therefore  there 
is  no  need  for  the  movement  of  the  will  to  be  referred  to  the 
movement  of  the  heavens,  as  to  its  cause. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  movements  of  the  human  body  are 
reduced,  as  to  their  cause,  to  the  movement  of  a  heavenly 
body;  in  so  far  as  the  disposition  suitable  to  a  particular 
movement,  is  somewhat  due  to  the  influence  of  heavenly 
bodies; — also,  in  so  far  as  the  sensitive  appetite  is  stirred 
by  the  influence  of  heavenly  bodies; — and  again,  in  so  far 
as  exterior  bodies  are  moved  in  accordance  with  the  move- 
ment of  heavenly  bodies,  at  whose  presence,  the  will  begins 
to  will  or  not  to  will  something ;  for  instance,  when  the  body 
is  chilled,  we  begin  to  wish  to  make  the  fire.  But  this 
movement  of  the  will  is  on  the  part  of  the  object  offered 
from  without :  not  on  the  part  of  an  inward  instigation. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  stated  above  (C/.  P.  I.,  Q.  LXXXIV., 
AA.  6,  7)  the  sensitive  appetite  is  the  act  of  a  bodily  organ. 
Wherefore  there  is  no  reason  why  man  should  not  be  prone 
to  anger  or  concupiscence,  or  some  like  passion,  by  reason 

*  Odyssey  xviii.  135. 

IT.   I  9 


130  QUESTION  IX 

of  the  influence  of  heavenly  bodies,  just  as  by  reason  of  his 
natural  complexion.  For  the  majority  of  men  are  led  by 
the  passions,  which  the  wise  alone  resist.  Consequently, 
in  the  majority  of  cases  predictions  about  human  acts, 
gathered  from  the  observation  of  heavenly  bodies,  are  ful- 
filled. Nevertheless,  as  Ptolemy  says  {Centiloquium  v.), 
the  wise  man  governs  the  stars  :  which  is  as  though  to  say 
that  by  resisting  his  passions,  he  opposes  his  will,  which  is 
free  and  nowise  subject  to  the  movement  of  the  heavens, 
to  suchlike  effects  of  the  heavenly  bodies. 

Or,  as  Augustine  says  [Gen.  ad  lit.  ii.) :  We  must  confess  that 
when  the  truth  is  foretold  by  astrologers,  this  is  due  to  some 
most  hidden  inspiration,  to  which  the  human  mind  is  subject 
without  knowing  it.  And  since  this  is  done  in  order  to  deceive 
man,  it  must  be  the  work  of  the  lying  spirits. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  the  will  is  moved  by  god  alone,  as  exterior 

principle  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  not  moved  by  God 
alone  as  exterior  principle.  For  it  is  natural  that  the 
inferior  be  moved  by  its  superior :  thus  the  lower  bodies  are 
moved  by  the  heavenly  bodies.  But  there  is  something 
which  is  higher  than  the  will  of  man  and  below  God,  namely, 
the  angel.  Therefore  man's  will  can  be  moved  by  an  angel 
also,  as  exterior  principle. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  act  of  the  will  follows  the  act  of  the 
intellect.  But  man's  intellect  is  reduced  to  act,  not  by  God 
alone,  but  also  by  the  angel  who  enlightens  it.  For  the 
same  reason,  therefore,  the  will  also  is  moved  by  an  angel. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  God  is  not  cause  of  other  than  good  things, 
according  to  Gen.  i.  31:  God  saw  all  the  things  that  He  had 
made,  and  they  were  very  good.  If,  therefore,  man's  will  were 
moved  by  God  alone,  it  would  never  be  moved  to  evil :  and 
yet  it  is  the  will  whereby  we  sin  and  whereby  we  do  right,  as 
Augustine  says  (Retract,  i.). 


WHAT  MOVES  THE  WILL  131 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Phil.  ii.  13) :  It  is  God  Who 
worketh  in  us  (Vulg., — you)  both  to  will  and  to  accomplish. 

I  answer  that,  The  movement  of  the  will  is  from  within, 
as  also  is  the  movement  of  nature.  Now  although  it  is 
possible  for  something  to  move  a  natural  thing,  without  being 
the  cause  of  the  thing  moved,  yet  that  alone,  which  is  in 
some  way  the  cause  of  a  thing's  nature,  can  cause  a  natural 
movement  in  that  thing.  For  a  stone  is  moved  upwards 
by  a  man,  who  is  not  the  cause  of  the  stone's  nature;  but 
the  natural  movement  of  the  stone  is  caused  by  no  other 
than  the  cause  of  its  nature.  Wherefore  it  is  said  in 
Phys.  viii.,  that  the  generator  moves  locally  heavy  and  light 
things.  Accordingly  man  endowed  with  a  will  is  sometimes 
moved  by  something  that  is  not  his  cause;  but  that  his 
voluntary  movement  be  from  an  exterior  principle  that  is 
not  the  cause  of  his  will,  is  impossible. 

Now  the  cause  of  the  will  can  be  none  other  than  God. 
And  this  is  evident  for  two  reasons.  First,  because  the  will 
is  a  power  of  the  rational  soul,  which  is  caused  by  God  alone, 
by  creation,  as  was  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XC,  A.  2). — 
Secondly,  it  is  evident  from  the  fact  that  the  will  is  ordained 
to  the  universal  good.  Wherefore  nothing  else  can  be  the 
cause  of  the  will,  except  God  Himself,  Who  is  the  universal 
good :  while  every  other  good  is  good  by  participation, 
and  is  some  particular  good ;  and  a  particular  cause  does  not 
give  a  universal  inclination.  Hence  neither  can  primary 
matter,  which  is  potentiality  to  all  forms,  be  created  by 
some  particular  agent. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  An  angel  is  not  above  man  in  such  a  way  as 
to  be  the  cause  of  his  will;  as  the  heavenly  bodies  are  the 
causes  of  natural  forms,  from  which  result  the  natural  move- 
ments of  natural  bodies. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Man's  intellect  is  moved  by  an  angel,  on  the 
part  of  the  object,  which  by  the  power  of  the  angelic  light, 
is  proposed  to  man's  knowledge.  And  in  this  way  the  will 
also  can  be  moved  by  a  creature  from  without,  as  stated 
above  (A.  4). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  God  moves  man's  will,   as  the  Universal 


132  QUESTION  IX 

Mover,  to  the  universal  object  of  the  will,  which  is  good. 
And  without  this  universal  motion,  man  cannot  will  any- 
thing. But  man  determines  himself  by  his  reason,  to  will 
this  or  that,  which  is  true  or  apparent  good. — Nevertheless, 
sometimes  God  moves  some  specially  to  the  willing  of  some- 
thing determinate,  which  is  good;  as  in  the  case  of  those 
whom  He  moves  by  grace,  as  we  shall  state  later  on 
(Q.  CIX.,  A.  2). 


QUESTION  X. 

OF  THE  MANNER  IN  WHICH  THE  WILL  IS  MOVED. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  manner  in  which  the  will  is 
moved.  Under  this  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)   Whether   the   will   is   moved   to   anything   naturally  ? 

(2)  Whether   it   is   moved   of   necessity    by    its    object  ? 

(3)  Whether  it  is  moved  of  necessity  by  the  lower  appetite  ? 

(4)  Whether  it  is  moved  of  necessity  by  the  exterior  mover 
which  is  God  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  the  will  is  moved  to  anything  naturally? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  not  moved  to  any- 
thing naturally.  For  the  natural  agent  is  condivided  with 
the  voluntary  agent,  as  stated  at  the  beginning  of  Phys.  ii. 
Therefore  the  will  is  not  moved  to  anything  naturally. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  that  which  is  natural  is  in  a  thing  always: 
as  being  hot  is  in  fire.  But  no  movement  is  always  in  the 
will.     Therefore  no  movement  is  natural  to  the  will. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  nature  is  determinate  to  one  thing: 
whereas  the  will  is  referred  to  opposites.  Therefore  the  will 
wills  nothing  naturally. 

On  the  contrary,  The  movement  of  the  will  follows  the 
movement  of  the  intellect.  But  the  intellect  understands 
some  things  naturally.  Therefore  the  will,  too,  wills  some 
things  naturally. 

/  answer  that,  As  Boethius  says  (De  Duabiis  Nat.)  and  the 
Philosopher  also  {Metaph.  v.)  the  word  nature  is  used  in  a 

133 


134  QUESTION  X 

manifold  sense.  For  sometimes  it  stands  for  the  intrinsic 
principle  in  movable  things.  In  this  sense  nature  is  either 
matter  or  the  material  form,  as  stated  in  Phys.  ii. — In 
another  sense  nature  stands  for  any  substance,  or  even  for 
any  being.  And  in  this  sense,  that  is  said  to  be  natural  to 
a  thing  which  befits  it  in  respect  of  its  substance.  And  this 
is  that  which  of  itself  is  in  a  thing.  Now  all  things  that  do 
not  of  themselves  belong  to  the  thing  in  which  they  are, 
are  reduced  to  something  which  belongs  of  itself  to  that  thing, 
as  to  their  principle.  Wherefore,  taking  nature  in  this 
sense,  it  is  necessary  that  the  principle  of  whatever  belongs 
to  a  thing,  be  a  natural  principle.  This  is  evident  in  regard 
to  the  intellect:  for  the  principles  of  intellectual  knowledge 
are  naturally  known.  In  like  manner  the  principle  of 
voluntary  movements  must  be  something  naturally  willed. 

Now  this  is  good  in  general,  to  which  the  will  tends 
naturally,  as  does  each  power  to  its  object;  and  again  it  is 
the  last  end,  which  stands  in  the  same  relation  to  things 
appetible,  as  the  first  principles  of  demonstrations  to  things 
intelligible:  and,  speaking  generally,  it  is  all  those  things 
which  belong  to  the  wilier  according  to  his  nature.  For 
it  is  not  only  things  pertaining  to  the  will  that  the  will 
desires,  but  also  that  which  pertains  to  each  power,  and  to 
the  entire  man.  Wherefore  man  wills  naturally  not  only 
the  object  of  the  will,  but  also  other  things  that  are  appro- 
priate to  the  other  powers;  such  as  the  knowledge  of  truth, 
which  befits  the  intellect;  and  to  be  and  to  live  and  other 
like  things  which  regard  the  natural  well-being ;  all  of  which  are 
included  in  the  object  of  the  will,  as  so  many  particular  goods. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  will  is  distinct  from  nature  as  one  kind 
of  cause  is  from  another;  for  some  things  happen  naturally 
and  some  are  done  voluntarily.  There  is,  however,  another 
manner  of  causing  that  is  proper  to  the  will,  which  is 
mistress  of  its  act,  besides  the  manner  proper  to  nature, 
which  is  determinate  to  one  thing.  But  since  the  will  is 
founded  on  some  nature,  it  is  necessary  that  the  movement 
proper  to  nature  be  shared  by  the  will,  to  some  extent:  just 
as  what  belongs  to  a  previous  cause  is  shared  by  a  subsequent 


HOW  THE  WILL  IS  MOVED  135 

cause.  Because  in  every  thing,  being  itself  which  is  from 
nature,  precedes  voHtion,  which  is  from  the  will.  And 
hence  it  is  that  the  will  wills  something  naturally. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  In  the  case  of  natural  things,  that  which  is 
natural,  as  a  result  of  the  form  only,  is  always  in  them 
actually,  as  heat  is  in  fire.  But  that  which  is  natural  as  a 
result  of  matter,  is  not  always  in  them  actually,  but  sometimes 
only  in  potentiality :  because  form  is  act,  whereas  matter  is 
potentiality.  Now  movement  is  the  act  of  that  which  is  in 
potentiality  (Aristotle,  Phys.  iii).  Wherefore  that  which 
belongs  to,  or  results  from,  movement,  in  regard  to  natural 
things,  is  not  always  in  them.  Thus  fire  does  not  always 
move  upwards,  but  only  when  it  is  outside  its  own  place.* 
And  in  like  manner  it  is  not  necessary  that  the  will  (which 
is  reduced  from  potentiality  to  act,  when  it  wills  something), 
should  always  be  in  the  act  of  volition ;  but  only  when  it  is 
in  a  certain  determinate  disposition.  But  God's  will,  which 
is  pure  act,  is  always  in  the  act  of  volition. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  To  every  nature  there  is  one  thing  corre- 
sponding, proportionate,  however,  to  that  nature.  For  to 
nature  considered  as  a  genus,  there  corresponds  something 
one  generically;  and  to  nature  as  species  there  corresponds 
something  one  specifically ;  and  to  the  individualized  nature 
there  corresponds  some  one  individual.  Since,  therefore, 
the  will  is  an  immaterial  power,  like  the  intellect,  some  one 
general  thing  corresponds  to  it,  which  is  the  good;  just  as  to 
the  intellect  there  corresponds  some  one  general  thing,  which 
is  the  true,  or  being,  or  what  a  thing  is.  And  under  good  in 
general  are  included  many  particular  goods,  to  none  of  which 
is  the  will  determined. 

*  The  Aristotelian  theory  was  that  fire's  proper  place  is  the 
fiery  heaven,  i.e.,  the  Empyrean. 


136  .  QUESTION  X 


Second  Article, 
whether  the  will  is  moved,  of  necessity,  by  its 

OBJECT  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  moved,  of  necessity, 
by  its  object.  For  the  object  of  the  will  is  compared  to  the 
will  as  mover  to  movable,  as  stated  in  De  Anima  iii.  But  a 
mover,  if  it  be  sufficient,  moves  the  movable  of  necessity. 
Therefore  the  will  can  be  moved  of  necessity  by  its  object. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  just  as  the  will  is  an  immaterial  power, 
so  is  the  intellect:  and  both  powers  are  ordained  to  a  uni- 
versal object,  as  stated  above  (A.  i  ^^  3).  But  the  intellect 
is  moved,  of  necessity,  by  its  object:  therefore  the  will  also, 
by  its  object. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  whatever  one  wills,  is  either  the  end,  or 
something  ordained  to  an  end.  But,  seemingly,  one  wills  an 
end  necessarily :  because  it  is  like  the  principle  in  speculative 
matters,  to  which  principle  one  assents  of  necessity.  Now 
the  end  is  the  reason  for  willing  the  means ;  and  so  it  seems 
that  we  will  the  means  also  necessarily.  Therefore  the  will 
is  moved  of  necessity  by  its  object. 

On  the  contrary,  The  rational  powers,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  {Metaph.  viii.)  are  directed  to  opposites.  But 
the  will  is  a  rational  power,  since  it  is  in  the  reason,  as  stated 
in  De  Anima  iii.  Therefore  the  will  is  directed  to  opposites. 
Therefore  it  is  not  moved,  of  necessity,  to  either  of  the 
opposites. 

I  answer  that,  The  will  is  moved  in  two  ways :  first,  as  to  the 
exercise  of  its  act;  secondly,  as  to  the  specification  of  its  act, 
derived  from  the  object.  As  to  the  iirst  way,  no  object 
moves  the  will  necessarily,  for  no  matter  what  the  object  be, 
it  is  in  man's  power  not  to  think  of  it,  and  consequently 
not  to  will  it  actually.  But  as  to  the  second  manner  of 
motion,  the  will  is  moved  by  one  object  necessarily,  by 
another  not.  For  in  the  movement  of  a  power  by  its  object, 
we  must  consider  under  what  aspect  the  object  moves  the 


HOW  THE  WILL  IS  MOVED  137 

power.  For  the  visible  moves  the  sight,  under  the  aspect  of 
colour  actually  visible.  Wherefore  if  colour  be  offered  to 
the  sight,  it  moves  the  sight  necessarily :  unless  one  turns 
one's  eyes  away ;  which  belongs  to  the  exercise  of  the  act. 
But  if  the  sight  were  confronted  with  something  not  in  all 
respects  coloured  actually,  but  only  so  in  some  respects, 
and  in  other  respects  not,  the  sight  would  not  of  necessity 
see  such  an  object :  for  it  might  look  at  that  part  of  the  object 
which  is  not  actually  coloured,  and  thus  it  would  not  see  it. 
Now  just  as  the  actually  coloured  is  the  object  of  sight,  so 
is  good  the  obj  ec t  of  the  will .  Wherefore  if  the  will  be  offered 
an  object  which  is  good  universally  and  from  every  point 
of  view,  the  will  tends  to  it  of  necessity,  if  it  wills  anything 
at  all;  since  it  cannot  will  the  opposite.  If,  on  the  other 
hand,  the  will  is  offered  an  object,  that  is  not  good  from 
every  point  of  view,  it  will  not  tend  to  it  of  necessity. — 
And  since  lack  of  any  good  whatever,  is  a  non-good,  conse- 
quently, that  good  alone  which  is  perfect  and  lacking  in 
nothing,  is  such  a  good  that  the  will  cannot  not- will  it :  and 
this  is  Happiness.  Whereas  any  other  particular  goods, 
in  so  far  as  they  are  lacking  in  some  good,  can  be  regarded  as 
non-goods :  and  from  this  point  of  view,  they  can  be  set  aside 
or  approved  by  the  will,  which  can  tend  to  one  and  the  same 
thing  from  various  points  of  view. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  sufficient  mover  of  a  power  is  none  but 
that  object  that  in  every  respect  presents  the  aspect  of  the 
mover  of  that  power.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  lacking 
in  any  respect,  it  will  not  move  of  necessity,  as  stated 
above. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  intellect  is  moved,  of  necessity,  by  an 
object,  which  is  such  as  to  be  always  and  necessarily  true: 
but  not  by  that  which  may  be  either  true  or  false — viz.,  by 
that  which  is  contingent:  as  we  have  said  of  the  good. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  last  end  moves  the  will  necessarily, 
because  it  is  the  perfect  good.  In  like  manner  whatever  is 
ordained  to  that  end,  and  without  which  the  end  cannot  be 
attained,  such  as  to  be  and  to  live,  and  the  like.  But  other 
things  without  which  the  end  can  be  gained,  are  not  neces- 


138  QUESTION  X 

sarily  willed  by  one  who  wills  the  end :  just  as  he  who  assents 
to  the  principle,  does  not  necessarily  assent  to  the  conclu- 
sions, without  which  the  principles  can  still  be  true. 


Third  Article. 

whether  the  will  is  moved,  of  necessity,  by  the 

lower  appetite  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  moved  of  necessity 
by  a  passion  of  the  lower  appetite.  For  the  Apostle  says 
(Rom.  vii.  19) :  The  good  which  I  will  I  do  not ;  hut  the  evil 
which  I  will  not,  that  I  do  :  and  this  is  said  by  reason  of  con- 
cupiscence, which  is  a  passion.  Therefore  the  will  is  moved 
of  necessity  by  a  passion. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  as  stated  in  Ethic  iii.,  according  as  a  man 
is,  such  does  the  end  seem  to  him.  But  it  is  not  in  man's 
power  to  cast  aside  a  passion  at  once.  Therefore  it  is  not 
in  man's  power  not  to  will  that  to  which  the  passion  inclines 
him. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  a  universal  cause  is  not  applied  to  a 
particular  effect,  except  by  means  of  a  particular  cause: 
wherefore  the  universal  reason  does  not  move  save  by  means 
of  a  particular  estimation,  as  stated  in  De  Anima  iii.  But 
as  the  universal  reason  is  to  the  particular  estimation,  so  is 
the  will  to  the  sensitive  appetite.  Therefore  the  will  is  not 
moved  to  will  something  particular,  except  through  the 
sensitive  appetite.  Therefore,  if  the  sensitive  appetite 
happen  to  be  disposed  to  something,  by  reason  of  a  passion, 
the  will  cannot  be  moved  in  a  contrary  sense. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  (Gen.  iv.  7) :  Thy  lust 
(Vulg., — The  lust  thereof)  shall  be  under  thee,  and  thou  shall 
have  dominion  over  it.  Therefore  man's  will  is  not  moved 
of  necessity  by  the  lower  appetite. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  2),  the  passion 
of  the  sensitive  appetite  moves  the  will,  in  so  far  as  the  will 
is  moved  by  its  object:  inasmuch  as,  to  wit,  man  through 
being  disposed  in  such  and  such  a  way  by  a  passion,  judges 


HOW  THE  WILL  IS  MOVED  139 

something  to  be  fitting  and  good,  which  he  would  not  judge 
thus  were  it  not  for  the  passion.  Now  this  influence  of  a 
passion  on  man  occurs  in  two  ways.  First,  so  that  his 
reason  is  wholly  bound,  so  that  he  has  not  the  use  of  reason : 
as  happens  in  those  who  through  a  violent  access  of  anger 
or  concupiscence  become  furious  or  insane,  just  as  they 
may  from  some  other  bodily  disorder ;  since  suchlike  passions 
do  not  take  place  without  some  change  in  the  body.  And 
of  such  the  same  is  to  be  said  as  of  irrational  animals,  which 
follow,  of  necessity,  the  impulse  of  their  passions:  for  in 
them  there  is  neither  movement  of  reason,  nor,  consequently, 
of  will. 

Sometimes,  however,  the  reason  is  not  entirely  engrossed 
by  the  passion,  so  that  the  judgment  of  reason  retains,  to 
a  certain  extent,  its  freedom:  and  thus  the  movement  of 
the  will  remains  in  a  certain  degree.  Accordingly  in  so  far 
as  the  reason  remains  free,  and  not  subject  to  the  passion, 
the  will's  movement,  which  also  remains,  does  not  tend,  of 
necessity  to  that  whereto  the  passion  inclines  it.  Conse- 
quently, either  there  is  no  movement  of  the  will  in  that  man, 
and  the  passion  alone  holds  its  sway :  or  if  there  be  a  move- 
ment of  the  will,  it  does  not  necessarily  follow  the  passion. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Although  the  will  cannot  prevent  the 
movement  of  concupiscence  from  arising,  of  which  the 
Apostle  says:  The  evil  which  I  will  not,  that  I  do — i.e.,  I 
desire  ;  yet  it  is  in  the  power  of  the  will  not  to  will  to  desire, 
or  not  to  consent  to  concupiscence.  And  thus  it  does  not 
necessarily  follow  the  movement  of  concupiscence. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Since  there  is  in  man  a  twofold  nature, 
intellectual  and  sensitive;  sometimes  man  is  such  and  such 
uniformly  in  respect  of  his  whole  soul:  either  because  the 
sensitive  part  is  wholly  subject  to  his  reason,  as  in  the 
virtuous;  or  because  reason  is  entirely  engrossed  by  passion, 
as  in  a  madman.  But  sometimes,  although  reason  is  clouded 
by  passion,  yet  something  of  the  reason  remains  free.  And 
in  respect  of  this,  man  can  either  repel  the  passion  entirely, 
or  at  least  hold  himself  in  check  so  as  not  to  be  led  away  by 
the  passion.     For  when  thus  disposed,  since  man  is  variously 


140  QUESTION  X 

disposed  according  to  the  various  parts  of  the  soul,  a  thing 
appears  to  him  otherwise  according  to  his  reason,  than  it 
does  according  to  a  passion. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  will  is  moved  not  only  by  the  universal 
good  apprehended  by  the  reason,  but  also  by  good  appre- 
hended by  sense.  Wherefore  he  can  be  moved  to  some 
particular  good  independently  of  a  passion  of  the  sensitive 
appetite.  For  we  will  and  do  many  things  without  passion, 
and  through  choice  alone;  as  is  most  evident  in  those  cases 
wherein  reason  resists  passion. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  will  is  moved  of  necessity  by  the 
exterior  mover  which  is  god  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  moved  of  necessity 
by  God.  For  every  agent  that  cannot  be  resisted  moves 
of  necessity.  But  God  cannot  be  resisted,  because  His 
power  is  infinite;  wherefore  it  is  written  (Rom.  ix.  19) :  Who 
resisteth  His  will  ?-  Therefore  God  moves  the  will  of  neces- 
sity. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  will  is  moved  of  necessity  to  what- 
ever it  wills  naturally,  as  stated  above  (A.  2  ad  3).  But 
whatever  God  does  in  a  thing  is  natural  to  it,  as  Augustine 
says  {Contra  Faust,  xxvi).  Therefore  the  will  wills  of 
necessity  everything  to  which  God  moves  it. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  A  thing  is  possible,  if  nothing  impossible 
follows  from  its  being  supposed.  But  something  impossible 
follows  from  the  supposition  that  the  will  does  not  will  that 
to  which  God  moves  it :  because  in  that  case  God's  operation 
would  be  ineffectual.  Therefore  it  is  not  possible  for  the 
will  not  to  will  that  to  which  God  moves  it.  Therefore  it 
wills  it  of  necessity. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ecclus.  xv.  14) :  God  made 
man  from  the  beginning,  and  left  him  in  the  hand  of  his  own 
counsel.  Therefore  He  does  not  of  necessity  move  man's 
will. 


HOW  THE  WILL  IS  MOVED  141 

/  answer  that,  As  Dionysius  says  {Div.  Nom.  iv.)  it  belongs 
to  Divine  providence,  not  to  destroy  hut  to  preserve  the  nature 
of  things.  Wherefore  it  moves  all  things  in  accordance 
with  their  conditions ;  so  that  from  necessary  causes,  through 
the  Divine  motion,  effects  follow  of  necessity;  but  from 
contingent  causes,  effects  follow  contingently.  Since,  there- 
fore, the  will  is  an  active  principle,  not  determinate  to  one 
thing,  but  having  an  indifferent  relation  to  many  things, 
God  so  moves  it,  that  He  does  not  determine  it  of  necessity 
to  one  thing,  but  its  movement  remains  contingent  and  not 
necessary,  except  in  those  things  to  which  it  is  moved 
naturally. 

Reply  Ohj,  i.  The  Divine  will  extends  not  only  to  the  doing 
of  something  by  the  thing  which  He  moves,  but  also  to  its 
being  done  in  a  way  which  is  fitting  to  the  nature  of  that 
thing.  And  therefore  it  would  be  more  repugnant  to  the 
Divine  motion,  for  the  will  to  be  moved  of  necessity,  which 
is  not  fitting  to  its  nature;  than  for  it  to  be  moved  freely, 
which  is  becoming  to  its  nature. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  That  is  natural  to  a  thing,  which  God  so 
works  in  it  that  it  may  be  natural  to  it :  for  thus  is  something 
becoming  to  a  thing,  according  as  God  wishes  it  to  be  be- 
coming. Now  He  does  not  wish  that  whatever  He  works 
in  things  should  be  natural  to  them,  for  instance,  that  the 
dead  should  rise  again.  But  this  He  does  wish  to  be  natural 
to  each  thing, — that  it  be  subject  to  the  Divine  power. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  If  God  moves  the  will  to  anything,  it  is  in- 
compossible  with  this  supposition,  that  the  will  be  not 
moved  thereto.  But  it  is  not  impossible  simply.  Conse- 
quently it  does  not  follow  that  the  will  is  moved  by  God 
necessarily. 


QUESTION  XL 

OF  ENJOYMENT,*  WHICH  IS  AN  ACT  OF  THE  WILL. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  enjoyment:  concerning  which  there 
are  four  points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether  to  enjoy  is  an  act  of 
the  appetitive  power  ?  (2)  Whether  it  belongs  to  the 
rational  creature  alone,  or  also  to  irrational  animals  ? 
(3)  Whether  enjoyment  is  only  of  the  last  end  ?  (4)  Whether 
it  is  only  of  the  end  possessed  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  to  enjoy  is  an  act  of  the  appetitive  power  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  to  enjoy  belongs  not  only  to 
the  appetitive  power.  For  to  enjoy  seems  nothing  else 
than  to  receive  the  fruit.  But  it  is  the  intellect,  in  whose 
act  Happiness  consists,  as  shown  above  (Q.  III.,  A.  4),  that 
receives  the  fruit  of  human  life,  which  is  Happiness.  There- 
fore to  enjoy  is  not  an  act  of  the  appetitive  power,  but  of  the 
intellect. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  each  power  has  its  proper  end,  which  is 
its  perfection :  thus  the  end  of  sight  is  to  know  the  visible ; 
of  the  hearing,  to  perceive  sounds;  and  so  forth.  But  the 
end  of  a  thing  is  its  fruit.  Therefore  to  enjoy  belongs  to 
each  power,  and  not  only  to  the  appetite. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  enjoyment  implies  a  certain  delight. 
But  sensible  delight  belongs  to  sense,  which  delights  in  its 
object:    and    for    the    same    reason,    intellectual    delight 

*  Or,  Fruition. 
142 


ENJOYMENT  OR  FRUITION  143 

belongs  to  the  apprehensive,  and  not  to  the  appetitive 
power. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Doctr.  Christ,  iv.  and 
De  Trin.  x.) :  To  enjoy  is  to  adhere  lovingly  to  something  for 
its  own  sake.  But  love  belongs  to  the  appetitive  power. 
Therefore  also  to  enjoy  is  an  act  of  the  appetitive  power. 

I  answer  that,  Fruitio  (enjoyment)  and  fructus  (fruit)  seem 
to  refer  to  the  same,  one  being  derived  from  the  other; 
which  from  which,  matters  not  for  our  purpose;  though  it 
seems  probable  that  the  one  which  is  more  clearly  known, 
was  first  named.  Now  those  things  are  most  manifest  to 
us  which  appeal  most  to  the  senses :  wherefore  it  seems  that 
the  word  '  fruition '  is  derived  from  sensible  fruits.  But 
sensible  fruit  is  that  which  we  expect  the  tree  to  produce 
in  the  last  place,  and  in  which  a  certain  sweetness  is  to  be 
perceived.  Hence  fruition  seems  to  have  relation  to  love, 
or  to  the  delight  which  one  has  in  realizing  the  longed-for 
term,  which  is  the  end.  Now  the  end  and  the  good  is  the 
object  of  the  appetitive  power.  Wherefore  it  is  evident  that 
fruition  is  the  act  of  the  appetitive  power. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Nothing  hinders  one  and  the  same  thing 
from  belonging,  under  different  aspects,  to  different  powers. 
Accordingly  the  vision  of  God,  as  vision,  is  an  act  of  the 
intellect;  but  as  a  good  and  an  end,  is  the  object  of  the  will. 
And  as  such  is  the  fruition  thereof:  so  that  the  intellect 
attains  this  end,  as  the  executive  power,  but  the  will  as  the 
motive  power,  moving  (the  powers)  towards  the  end  and 
enjoying  the  end  attained. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  perfection  and  end  of  every  other  power 
is  contained  in  the  object  of  the  appetitive  power,  as  the 
proper  is  contained  in  the  common,  as  stated  above  (Q.  IX., 
A.  i).  Hence  the  perfection  and  end  of  each  power,  in  so 
far  as  it  is  a  good,  belongs  to  the  appetitive  power.  Where- 
fore the  appetitive  power  moves  the  other  powers  to  their 
ends;  and  itself  realizes  the  end,  when  each  of  them  reaches 
the  end. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  In  delight  there  are  two  things:  perception 
of  what  is  becoming;  and  this  belongs  to  the  apprehensive 


144  QUESTION  XI 

power;  and  complacency  in  that  which  is  offered  as  becoming : 
and  this  belongs  to  the  appetitive  power,  in  which  power 
delight  is  formally  completed. 


Second  Article. 

whether  to  enjoy  belongs  to  the  rational  creature 
alone,  or  also  to  irrational  animals  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  to  enjoy  belongs  to  men  alone. 
For  Augustine  says  (De  Doctr.  Christ,  i.)  that  it  is  given  to 
us  men  to  enjoy  and  to  use.  Therefore  other  animals  cannot 
enjoy. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  to  enjoy  relates  to  the  last  end.  But 
irrational  animals  cannot  obtain  the  last  end.  Therefore 
it  is  not  for  them  to  enjoy. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  just  as  the  sensitive  appetite  is  beneath 
the  intellectual  appetite,  so  is  the  natural  appetite  beneath 
the  sensitive.  If,  therefore,  to  enjoy  belongs  to  the  sensi- 
tive appetite,  it  seems  that  for  the  same  reason  it  can  belong 
to  the  natural  appetite.  But  this  is  evidently  false,  since 
the  latter  cannot  delight  in  anything.  Therefore  the  sensi- 
tive appetite  cannot  enjoy:  and  accordingly  enjoyment  is 
not  possible  for  irrational  animals. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Qq.  83):  It  is  not  so 
absurd  to  suppose  that  even  beasts  enjoy  their  food  and  any 
bodily  pleasure. 

I  answer  that,  As  was  stated  above  (A.  i)  to  enjoy  is 
not  the  act  of  the  power  that  achieves  the  end  as  executor, 
but  of  the  power  that  commands  the  achievement  ;  for  it 
has  been  said  to  belong  to  the  appetitive  power.  Now 
things  void  of  reason  have  indeed  a  power  of  achieving  an 
end  by  way  of  execution,  as  that  by  which  a  heavy  body 
has  a  downward  tendency,  whereas  a  light  body  has  an 
upward  tendency.  Yet  the  power  of  command  in  respect 
of  the  end  is  not  in  them,  but  in  some  higher  nature,  which 
moves  all  nature  by  its  command,  just  as  in  things  endowed 
with  knowledge,  the  appetite  moves  the  other  powers  to 


ENJOYMENT  OR  FRUITION  145 

their  acts.  Wherefore  it  is  clear  that  things  void  of  knowledge, 
although  they  attain  an  end,  have  no  enjoyment  of  the  end: 
this  is  only  for  those  that  are  endowed  with  knowledge. 

Now  knowledge  of  the  end  is  twofold :  perfect  and  imper- 
fect. Perfect  knowledge  of  the  end,  is  that  whereby  not 
only  is  that  known  which  is  the  end  and  the  good,  but  also 
the  universal  formality  of  the  end  and  the  good;  and  such 
knowledge  belongs  to  the  rational  nature  alone.  On  the 
other  hand,  imperfect  knowledge  is  that  by  which  the  end 
and  the  good  are  known  in  the  particular.  Such  know- 
ledge is  in  irrational  animals:  whose  appetitive  powers  do 
not  command  with  freedom,  but  are  moved  according  to 
a  natural  instinct  to  whatever  they  apprehend.  Conse- 
quently, enjoyment  belongs  to  the  rational  nature,  in  a 
perfect  degree;  to  irrational  animals,  imperfectly;  to  other 
creatures,  not  at  all. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Augustine  is  speaking  there  of  perfect  enjoy- 
ment. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Enjoyment  need  not  be  of  the  last  end  simply ; 
but  of  that  which  each  one  chooses  for  his  last  end. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  sensitive  appetite  follows  some  know- 
ledge; not  so  the  natural  appetite,  especially  in  things  void 
of  knowledge. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Augustine  is  speaking  there  of  imperfect 
enjoyment.  This  is  clear  from  his  way  of  speaking:  for  he 
says  that  it  is  not  so  absurd  to  suppose  that  even  beasts  enjoy, 
that  is,  as  it  would  be,  if  one  were  to  say  that  they  use. 

Third  Article, 
whether  enjoyment  is  only  of  the  last  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  enjoyment  is  not  only  of  the 
last  end.  For  the  Apostle  says  (Philem.  20) :  Yea,  brother, 
may  I  enjoy  thee  in  the  Lord.  But  it  is  evident  that  Paul  had 
not  placed  his  last  end  in  a  man.  Therefore  to  enjoy  is  not 
only  of  the  last  end. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  What  we  enjoy  is  the  fruit.     But  the 

II.  I  10 


146  QUESTION  XI 

Apostle  says  (Gal.  v.  22):  The  fruit  of  the  Spirit  is  charity, 
joy,  peace,  and  other  like  things,  which  are  not  in  the  nature 
of  the  last  end.  Therefore  enjoyment  is  not  only  of  the  ]ast 
end. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  acts  of  the  will  reflect  on  one  another; 
for  I  will  to  will,  and  I  love  to  love.  But  to  enjoy  is  an  act 
of  the  will :  since  it  is  the  will  with  which  we  enjoy,  as  Augustine 
says  {De  Trin.  x.).  Therefore  a  man  enjoys  his  enjoyment. 
But  the  last  end  of  man  is  not  enjoyment,  but  the  uncreated 
good  alone,  which  is  God.  Therefore  enjoyment  is  not  only 
of  the  last  end. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  x.) :  A  man  does 
not  enjoy  that  which  he  desires  for  the  sake  of  something  else. 
But  the  last  end  alone  is  that  which  man  does  not  desire  for 
the  sake  of  something  else.  Therefore  enjoyment  is  of  the 
last  end  alone. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  i)  the  notion  of  fruit 
implies  two  things:  first  that  it  should  come  last;  second, 
that  it  should  calm  the  appetite  with  a  certain  sweetness  and 
delight.  Now  a  thing  is  last  either  simply  or  relatively; 
simply,  if  it  be  referred  to  nothing  else;  relatively,  if  it  is  the 
last  in  a  particular  series.  Therefore  that  which  is  last 
simply,  and  in  which  one  delights  as  in  the  last  end,  is  pro- 
perly called  fruit;  and  this  it  is  that  one  is  properly  said  to 
enjoy. — But  that  which  is  delightful  not  in  itself,  but  is 
desired,  only  as  referred  to  something  else,  e.g.,  a  bitter 
potion  for  the  sake  of  health,  can  nowise  be  called  fruit. — 
And  that  which  has  something  delightful  about  it,  to  which 
a  number  of  preceding  things  are  referred,  may  indeed  be 
called  fruit  in  a  certain  manner;  but  we  cannot  be  said  to 
enjoy  it  properly  or  as  though  it  answered  perfectly  to  the 
notion  of  fruit.  Hence  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  x.)  that 
we  enjoy  what  we  know,  when  the  delighted  will  is  at  rest  therein. 
But  its  rest  is  not  absolute  save  in  the  possession  of  the  last 
end :  for  as  long  as  something  is  looked  for,  the  movement  of 
the  will  remains  in  suspense,  although  it  has  reached  some- 
thing. Thus  in  local  movement,  although  any  point  be- 
tween the  two  terms  is  a  beginning  and  an  end,  yet  it  is  not 


ENJOYMENT  OR  FRUITION  147 

considered  as  an  actual  end,  except  when  the  movement 
stops  there. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  Augustine  says  {De  Doctr.  Christ,  i),  if  he 
had  said,  '  May  I  enjoy  thee,'  without  adding  '  in  the  Lord,* 
he  would  seem  to  have  set  the  end  of  his  love  in  him.  But  since 
he  added  that  he  set  his  end  in  the  Lord,  he  implied  his  desire  to 
enjoy  Him :  as  if  we  were  to  say  that  he  expressed  his  enjoy- 
ment of  his  brother  not  as  a  term  but  as  a  means. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Fruit  bears  one  relation  to  the  tree  that  bore 
it,  and  another  to  man  that  enjoys  it.  To  the  tree  indeed 
that  bore  it,  it  is  compared  as  effect  to  cause;  to  the  one 
enjoying  it,  as  the  final  object  of  his  longing  and  the  con- 
summation of  his  delight.  Accordingly  these  fruits  men- 
tioned by  the  Apostle  are  so  called  because  they  are  certain 
effects  of  the  Holy  Ghost  in  us,  wherefore  they  are  called 
fruits  of  the  Spirit :  but  not  as  though  we  are  to  enjoy  them 
as  our  last  end.  Or  we  may  say  with  Ambrose  that  they 
are  called  fruits  because  we  should  desire  them  for  their  own 
sake  :  not  indeed  as  though  they  were  not  ordained  to  the 
last  end;  but  because  they  are  such  that  we  ought  to  find 
pleasure  in  them. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  8;  Q.  II.,  A.  7),  we 
speak  of  an  end  in  a  twofold  sense :  first,  as  being  the  thing 
itself;  secondly,  as  the  attainment  thereof.  These  are  not, 
of  course,  two  ends,  but  one  end,  considered  in  itself,  and  in 
its  relation  to  something  else.  Accordingly  God  is  the  last 
end,  as  that  which  is  ultimately  sought  for:  while  the  enjoy- 
ment is  as  the  attainment  of  this  last  end.  And  so,  just  as 
God  is  not  one  end,  and  the  enjoyment  of  God,  anothei :  so 
it  is  the  same  enjoyment  whereby  we  enjoy  God,  and  where- 
by we  enjoy  our  enjoyment  of  God.  And  the  same  applies 
to  created  happiness  which  consists  in  enjoyment. 


148  QUESTION  XI 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  enjoyment  is  only  of  the  end  possessed  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  enjoyment  is  only  of  the  end 
possessed.  For  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  x.)  that  to  enjoy  is 
to  use  joyfully,  with  the  joy,  not  of  hope,  but  of  possession.  But 
so  long  as  a  thing  is  not  had,  there  is  joy,  not  of  possession 
but  of  hope.  Therefore  enjoyment  is  only  of  the  end 
possessed. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  as  stated  above  (A.  3),  enjoyment  is  not 
properly  otherwise  than  of  the  last  end :  because  this  alone 
gives  rest  to  the  appetite.  But  the  appetite  has  no  rest  save 
in  the  possession  of  the  end.  Therefore  enjoyment,  pro- 
perly speaking,  is  only  of  the  end  possessed. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  to  enjoy  is  to  lay  hold  of  the  fruit.  But 
one  does  not  lay  hold  of  the  fruit  until  one  is  in  possession  of 
the  end.     Therefore  enjoyment  is  only  of  the  end  possessed. 

On  the  contrary,  To  enjoy  is  to  adhere  lovingly  to  something 
for  its  own  sake,  as  Augustine  says  (De  Doctr.  Christ,  i).  But 
this  is  possible,  even  in  regard  to  a  thing  which  is  not  in  our 
possession.  Therefore  it  is  possible  to  enjoy  the  end  even 
though  it  be  not  possessed. 

/  answer  that,  To  enjoy  implies  a  certain  relation  of  the 
will  to  the  last  end,  according  as  the  will  has  something  by 
way  of  last  end.  Now  an  end  is  possessed  in  two  ways; 
perfectly  and  imperfectly.  Perfectly,  when  it  is  possessed 
not  only  in  intention  but  also  in  reality;  imperfectly,  when 
it  is  possessed  in  intention  only.  Perfect  enjoyment,  there- 
fore, is  of  the  end  alieady  possessed:  but  imperfect  enjoy- 
ment is  also  of  the  end  possessed  not  really,  but  only  in 
intention. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Augustine  speaks  there  of  perfect  enjoyment. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  will  is  hindered  in  two  ways  from  being 
at  rest.  First  on  the  part  of  the  object;  by  reason  of  its  not 
being  the  last  end,  but  ordained  to  something  else :  secondly 
on  the  part  of  the  one  who  desires  the  end,  by  reason  of  his 


ENJOYMENT  OR  FRUITION  149 

not  being  yet  in  possession  of  it.  Now  it  is  the  object  that 
specifies  an  act:  but  on  the  agent  depends  the  manner  of 
acting,  so  that  the  act  be  perfect  or  imperfect,  as  compared 
with  the  actual  circumstances  of  the  agent.  Therefore 
enjoyment  of  anything  but  the  last  end  is  not  enjoyment 
properly  speaking,  as  falling  short  of  the  nature  of  enjoy- 
ment. But  enjoyment  of  the  last  end,  not  yet  possessed,  is 
enjoyment  properly  speaking,  but  imperfect,  on  account  of 
the  imperfect  way  in  which  it  is  possessed. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  One  is  said  to  lay  hold  of  or  to  have  an  end, 
not  only  in  reality,  but  also  in  intention,  as  stated  above. 


QUESTION  XII. 

OF    INTENTION. 

{In  Five  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  Intention:  concerning  which  there 
are  five  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  intention  is  an  act  of 
the  intellect  or  of  the  will  ?  (2)  Whether  it  is  only  of  the 
last  end  ?  (3)  Whether  one  can  intend  two  things  at  the 
same  time  ?  (4)  Whether  intention  of  the  end  is  the  same 
act  as  volition  of  the  means  ?  (5)  Whether  intention  is 
within  the  competency  of  irrational  animals  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  intention  is  an  act  of  the  intellect 
or  of  the  will  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  intention  is  an  act  of  the  intellect, 
and  not  of  the  will.  For  it  is  written  (Matth.  vi.  22) :  //  thy 
eye  he  single,  thy  whole  body  shall  he  lightsome  :  where,  accord- 
ing to  Augustine  (De  Serm.  Dom.  in  Monte  ii.)  the  eye 
signifies  intention.  But  since  the  eye  is  the  organ  of  sight, 
it  signifies  the  apprehensive  power.  Therefore  intention  is 
not  an  act  of  the  appetitive  but  of  the  apprehensive  power. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Augustine  says  (ihid.)  that  Our  Lord 
spoke  of  intention  as  a  light,  when  He  said  (Matth.  vi.  23) :  // 
the  light  that  is  in  thee  he  darkness,  etc.  But  light  pertains  to 
knowledge.     Therefore  intention  does  too. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  intention  implies  a  kind  of  ordaining  to 
an  end.  But  to  ordain  is  an  act  of  reason.  Therefore 
intention  belongs  not  to  the  will  but  to  the  reason. 

150 


INTENTION  151 

Obj.  4.  Further,  an  act  of  the  will  is  either  of  the  end  or  of 
the  means.  But  the  act  of  the  will  in  respect  of  the  end  is 
called  volition,  or  enjoyment;  with  regard  to  the  means,  it  is 
choice,  from  which  intention  is  distinct.  Therefore  it  is  not 
an  act  of  the  will. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  xi.)  that  the 
intention  of  the  will  unites  the  sight  to  the  object  seen  ;  and  the 
images  retained  in  the  memory,  to  the  penetrating  gaze  of  the 
soul's  inner  thought.     Therefore  intention  is  an  act  of  the  will . 

/  answer  that,  Intention,  as  the  very  word  denotes,  signifies, 
to  tend  to  something.  Now  both  the  action  of  the  mover  and 
the  movement  of  the  thing  moved,  tend  to  something.  But 
that  the  movement  of  the  thing  moved  tends  to  anything,  is 
due  to  the  action  of  the  mover.  Consequently  intention 
belongs  first  and  principally  to  that  which  moves  to  the  end : 
hence  we  say  that  an  architect  or  anyone  who  is  in  authority, 
by  his  command  moves  others  to  that  which  he  intends. 
Now  the  will  moves  all  the  other  powers  of  the  soul  to  the  end, 
as  shown  above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  i.).  Wherefore  it  is  evident  that 
intention,  properly  speaking,  is  an  act  of  the  will. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  eye  designates  intention  figuratively, 
not  because  intention  has  reference  to  knowledge,  but 
because  it  presupposes  knowledge,  which  proposes  to  the 
will,  the  end  to  which  the  latter  moves ;  thus  we  foresee  with 
the  eye  whither  we  should  tend  with  our  bodies. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Intention  is  called  a  light  because  it  is 
manifest  to  him  who  intends.  Wherefore  works  are  called 
darkness,  because  a  man  knows  what  he  intends,  but  knows 
not  what  the  result  may  be,  as  Augustine  expounds  (loc. 
cit.). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  will  does  not  ordain,  but  tends  to  some- 
thing according  to  the  order  of  reason.  Consequently  this 
word  intention  indicates  an  act  of  the  will,  presupposing  the 
act  whereby  the  reason  orders  something  to  the  end. 

Reply  Obj.  4.  Intention  is  an  act  of  the  will  in  regard  to  the 
end.  Now  the  will  stands  in  a  threefold  relation  to  the  end. 
First,  absolutely;  and  thus  we  have  volition,  whereby  we 
will  absolutely  to  have  health   and  so  forth.     Secondly,   it 


152  QUESTION  XII 

considers  the  end,  as  its  place  of  rest;  and  thus  enjoyment 
regards  the  end.  Thirdly,  it  considers  the  end  as  the  term 
towards  which  something  is  ordained;  and  thus  intention 
regards  the  end.  For  when  we  speak  of  intending  to  have 
health,  we  mean  not  only  that  we  will  to  have  it,  but  that 
we  will  to  have  it  by  means  of  something  else. 

Second  Article. 
/       whether  intention  is  only  of  the  last  end  ? 

V 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  intention  is  only  of  the  last  end. 
For  it  is  said  in  the  book  of  Prosper 's  Sentences :  The  intention 
of  the  heart  is  a  cry  to  God.  But  God  is  the  last  end  of  the 
human  heart.  Therefore  intention  always  regards  the  last  end. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  intention  regards  the  end  as  the  terminus, 
as  stated  above  (A.  i  ad  ^).  But  a  terminus  is  something 
last.     Therefore  intention  always  regards  the  last  end. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  just  as  intention  regards  the  end,  so  does 
enjoyment.  But  enjoyment  is  always  of  the  last  end. 
Therefore  intention  is  too. 

On  the  contrary,  There  is  but  one  last  end  of  human  wills, 
viz.,  Happiness,  as  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  7).  If,  therefore, 
intention  were  only  of  the  last  end,  men  would  not  have 
different  intentions:  which  is  evidently  false. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i.  ad  ^),  intention  re- 
gards the  end  as  a  terminus  of  the  movement  of  the  will. 
Now  a  terminus  of  movement  may  be  taken  in  two  ways. 
First,  the  very  last  terminus,  when  the  movement  comes  to 
a  stop;  this  is  the  terminus  of  the  whole  movement. 
Secondly,  some  point  midway,  which  is  the  beginning  of  one 
part  of  the  movement,  and  the  end  or  terminus  of  the  other. 
Thus  in  the  movement  from  A  to  C  through  B,  C  is  the  last 
terminus,  while  B  is  a  terminus,  but  not  the  last.  And 
intention  can  be  of  both.  Consequently  though  intention  is 
always  of  the  end,  it  need  not  be  always  of  the  last  end. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  intention  of  the  heart  is  called  a  cry  to 
God,  not  that  God  is  always  the  object  of  intention,  but 


INTENTION  "  153 

because  He  sees  our  intention. — -Or  because,  when  we  pray, 
we  direct  our  intention  to  God,  which  intention  has  the  force 
of  a  cry. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  terminus  is  something  last,  not  always  in 
respect  of  the  whole,  but  sometimes  in  respect  of  a  part. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Enjoyment  impHes  rest  in  the  end;  and  this 
belongs  to  the  last  end  alone.  But  intention  implies  move- 
ment towards  an  end,  not  rest.  Wherefore  the  comparison 
proves  nothing. 

Third  Article. 

whether  one  can  intend  two  things  at 
the  same  time  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  one  cannot  intend  two  things  at 
the  same  time.  For  Augustine  says  (De  Serm.  Dom.  in 
Monte  ii.)  that  man's  intention  cannot  be  directed  at  the 
same  time  to  God  and  to  bodily  benefits.  Therefore,  for 
the  same  reason,  neither  to  any  other  two  things. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  intention  designates  a  movement  of  the 
will  towards  a  terminus.  Now  there  cannot  be  several 
termini  in  the  same  direction  of  one  movement.  Therefore 
the  will  cannot  intend  several  things  at  the  same  time. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  intention  presupposes  an  act  of  reason 
or  of  the  intellect.  But  it  is  not  possible  to  understand  several 
things  at  the  same  time,  according  to  the  Philosopher  {Topic. 
ii.).  Therefore  neither  is  it  possible  to  intend  several  things 
at  the  same  time. 

On  the  contrary,  Art  imitates  nature.  Now  nature  intends 
two  purposes  by  means  of  one  instrument :  thus  the  tongue  is 
for  the  purpose  of  taste  and  speech  {De  Anima  ii.).  Therefore, 
for  the  same  reason,  art  or  reason  can  at  the  same  time  direct 
one  thing  to  two  ends:  so  that  one  can  intend  several  ends 
at  the  same  time. 

I  answer  that,  The  expression  two  things  may  be  taken  in 
two  ways:  they  may  be  ordained  to  one  another  or  not  so 
ordained.  And  if  they  be  ordained  to  one  another,  it  is 
evident,  from  what  has  been  said,  that  a  man  can  intend 


154  QUESTION  XII 

many  things  at  the  same  time.  For  intention  is  not  only  of 
the  last  end,  as  stated  above  (A.  2),  but  also  of  an  inter- 
mediary end.  Now  a  man  intends  at  the  same  time,  both 
the  proximate  and  the  last  end ;  as  the  mixing  of  a  medicine 
and  the  giving  of  health. 

But  if  we  take  two  things  that  are  not  ordained  to  one 
another,  thus  also  a  man  can  intend  several  things  at  the 
same  time.  This  is  evident  from  the  fact  that  a  man  prefers 
one  thing  to  another  because  it  is  the  better  of  the  two .  Now 
one  of  the  reasons  for  which  one  thing  is  better  than  another 
is  that  it  is  available  for  more  purposes :  wherefore  one  thing 
can  be  chosen  in  preference  to  another,  because  of  the  greater 
number  of  purposes  for  which  it  is  available:  so  that  evi- 
dently a  man  can  intend  several  things  at  the  same  time. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Augustine  means  to  say  that  man  cannot 
at  the  same  time  direct  his  intention  to  God  and  to  bodily 
benefits,  as  to  two  last  ends:  since,  as  stated  above  (Q.  L, 
A.  5),  one  man  cannot  have  several  last  ends. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  There  can  be  several  termini  ordained  to 
one  another,  of  the  same  movement  and  in  the  same  direction ; 
but  not  unless  they  be  ordained  to  one  another.  At  the  same 
time  it  must  be  observed  that  what  is  not  one  in  reality  may 
be  taken  as  one  by  the  reason.  Now  intention  is  a  move- 
ment of  the  will  to  something  already  ordained  by  the 
reason,  as  stated  above  (A.  i.  ad  3).  Wherefore  where  we 
have  many  things  in  reality,  we  may  take  them  as  one  term 
of  intention,  in  so  far  as  the  reason  takes  them  as  one: 
either  because  two  things  concur  in  the  intergrity  of  one 
whole,  as  a  proper  measure  of  heat  and  cold  conduce  to 
health :  or  because  two  things  are  included  in  one  which  may 
be  intended.  For  instance,  the  acquiring  of  wine  and  clothing 
is  included  in  wealth,  as  in  something  common  to  both: 
wherefore  nothing  hinders  the  man  who  intends  to  acquire 
wealth,  from  intending  both  the  others. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XII.,  A.  10; 
Q.  LVIIL,  A.  2;  Q.  LXXXV.,  A.  4),  it  is  possible  to  under-^ 
stand  several  things   at   the  same  time,   in  so   far   as,   in 
some  way,  they  are  one. 


INTENTION  155 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  intention  of  the  end  is  the  same  act 
as  the  volition  of  the  means  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  intention  of  the  end  and  the 
vohtion  of  the  means  are  not  one  and  the  same  movement. 
For  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  xi.)  that  the  will  to  see  the 
window,  has  for  its  end  the  seeing  of  the  window  ;  and  is 
another  act  from  the  will  to  see,  through  the  window,  the  passer s- 
hy.  But  that  I  should  will  to  see  the  passers-by,  through 
the  window,  belongs  to  intention ;  whereas  that  I  will  to  see 
the  window,  belongs  to  the  voliton  of  the  means.  Therefore 
intention  of  the  end  and  the  willing  of  the  means  are  distinct 
movements  of  the  will. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  acts  are  distinct  according  to  their  objects. 
But  the  end  and  the  means  are  distinct  objects.  Therefore 
the  intention  of  the  end  and  the  willing  of  the  means  are 
distinct  movements  of  the  will. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  willing  of  the  means  is  called  choice. 
But  choice  and  intention  are  not  the  same.  Therefore 
intention  of  the  end  and  the  willing  of  the  means  are  not  the 
same  movement  of  the  will. 

On  the  contrary,  The  means  in  relation  to  the  end,  are  as  the 
mid-space  to  the  terminus.  Now  it  is  all  the  same  move- 
ment that  passes  through  the  mid-space  to  the  terminus,  in 
natural  things.  Therefore  in  things  pertaining  to  the  will, 
the  intention  of  the  end  is  the  same  movement  as  the  willing 
of  the  means. 

I  answer  that,  The  movement  of  the  will  to  the  end  and  to 
the  means  can  be  considered  in  two  ways.  First,  according 
as  the  will  is  moved  to  each  of  the  aforesaid  absolutely  and 
in  itself.  And  thus  there  are  simply  two  movements  of  the 
will  to  them.  Secondly,  it  may  be  considered  accordingly  as 
the  will  is  moved  to  the  means  for  the  sake  of  the  end :  and 
thus  the  movement  of  the  will  to  the  end  and  its  movement 
to  the  means  are  one  and  the  same  thing.     For  when  I  say : 


156  '  QUESTION  XII 

I  wish  to  take  medicine  for  the  sake  of  health,  I  signify  no  more 
than  one  movement  of  my  will.  And  this  is  because  the 
end  is  the  formal  object  in  willing  the  means.  Now  it  is  the 
same  act  that  lays  hold  of  the  formal  object,  and  of  the 
formal  reason  of  laying  hold  of  it :  thus  it  is  the  same  act  of 
sight  that  perceives  colour  and  light,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  VIII.,  A.  3  ad  2).  And  the  same  applies  to  the  intellect; 
for  if  it  consider  principle  and  conclusion  absolutely,  it 
considers  each  by  a  distinct  act;  but  when  it  assents  to  the 
conclusion  on  account  of  the  principles,  there  is  but  one  act 
of  the  intellect. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Augustine  is  speaking  of  seeing  the  window 
and  of  seeing,  through  the  window,  the  passers-by,  according 
as  the  will  is  moved  to  either  absolutely. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  end,  considered  as  a  thing,  and  the  means 
to  that  end,  are  distinct  objects  of  the  will.  But  in  so  far  as 
the  end  is  the  formal  object  in  willing  the  means,  they  are 
the  one  and  the  same  object. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  A  movement  which  is  one  as  to  the  subject, 
may  differ,  according  to  our  way  of  looking  at  it,  as  to  its 
beginning  and  end,  as  in  the  case  of  ascent  and  descent 
(Physic,  iii.).  Accordingly,  in  so  far  as  the  movement  of  the 
will  is  to  the  means,  as  ordained  to  the  end,  it  is  called 
choice  :  but  the  movement  of  the  will  to  the  end  as  acquired 
by  the  means,  is  called  intention.  A  sign  of  this  is  that  we 
can  have  intention  of  the  end  without  having  determined 
the  means  which  are  the  object  of  choice. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  intention  is  within  the  competency 
of  irrational  animals  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  1.  It  seems  that  irrational  animals  intend  the 
end.  For  in  things  void  of  reason  nature  stands  further 
apart  from  the  rational  nature,  than  does  the  sensitive 
nature  in  irrational  animals.  But  nature  intends  the  end 
even  in   things  void  of  reason,   as  is  proved  in   Phys.  ii. 


INTENTION  157 

Much  more,  therefore,  do  irrational  animals  intend  the 
end. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  just  as  intention  is  of  the  end,  so  is  enjoy- 
ment. But  enjoyment  is  in  irrational  animals,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XL,  A.  2).     Therefore  intention  is  too. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  to  intend  an  end  belongs  to  one  who  acts 
for  an  end;  since  to  intend  is  nothing  else  than  to  tend  to 
something.  But  irrational  animals  act  for  an  end;  for  an 
animal  is  moved  either  to  seek  food,  or  to  do  something  of 
the  kind.     Therefore  irrational  animals  intend  an  end. 

On  the  contrary,  Intention  of  an  end  implies  ordaining 
something  to  an  end:  which  belongs  to  reason.  Since 
therefore  irrational  animals  are  void  of  reason,  it  seems  that 
they  do  not  intend  an  end. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  to  intend  is  to  tend 
to  something;  and  this  belongs  to  the  mover  and  to  the 
moved.  According,  therefore,  as  that  which  is  moved  to  an 
end  by  another,  is  said  to  intend  the  end,  thus  nature  is  said 
to  intend  an  end,  as  being  moved  to  its  end  by  God,  as  the 
arrow  is  moved  by  the  archer.  And  in  this  way,  irrational 
animals  intend  an  end,  in  as  much  as  they  are  moved  to 
something  by  natural  instinct. — The  other  way  of  intending 
an  end  belongs  to  the  mover;  according  as  he  ordains  the 
movement  of  something,  either  his  own  or  another's,  to  an 
end.  This  belongs  to  reason  alone.  Wherefore  irrational 
animals  do  not  intend  an  end  in  this  way,  which  is  to  intend 
properly  and  principally,  as  stated  above  (A.  i). 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  argument  takes  intention  in  the  sense 
of  being  moved  to  an  end. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Enjoyment  does  not  imply  the  ordaining  of 
one  thing  to  another,  as  intention  does;  but  absolute  repose 
in  the  end. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Irrational  animals  are  moved  to  an  end,  not 
as  though  they  thought  that  they  can  gain  the  end  by  this 
movement;  this  belongs  to  one  that  intends;  but  through 
desiring  the  end  by  natural  instinct,  they  are  moved  to  an 
end,  moved,  as  it  were,  by  another,  like  other  things  that 
are  moved  naturally. 


QUESTION  XIII. 

OF  CHOICE,  WHICH  IS  AN  ACT  OF  THE  WILL  WITH 
REGARD  TO  THE  MEANS. 

{In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  acts  of  the  will  with  regard  to  the 
means.  There  are  three  of  them :  to  choose,  to  consent,  and 
to  use.  And  choice  is  preceded  by  counsel.  First  of  all, 
then,  we  must  consider  choice;  secondly,  counsel;  thirdly, 
consent;  fourthly,  use.  * 

Concerning  choice  there  are  six  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Of 
what  power  is  it  the  act;  of  the  will  or  of  the  reason  ?  (2) 
Whether  choice  is  within  the  competency  of  irrational 
animals  ?  (3)  Whether  choice  is  only  of  the  means,  or 
sometimes  also  of  the  end  ?  (4)  Whether  choice  is  only  of 
things  that  we  do  ourselves  ?  (5)  Whether  choice  is  only  of 
possible  things  ?  (6)  Whether  man  chooses  of  necessity  or 
freely  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  choice  is  an  act  of  will  or  of  reason  ? 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  choice  is  an  act,  not  of  will  but 
of  reason.  For  choice  implies  comparison,  whereby  one  is 
given  preference  to  another.  But  to  compare  is  an  act  of 
reason.     Therefore  choice  is  an  act  of  reason. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  it  is  for  the  same  to  form  a  syllogism,  as  to 
draw  the  conclusion.  But,  in  practical  matters,  it  is  the 
reason  that  forms  syllogisms.  Since  therefore  choice  is  a 
kind  of  conclusion  in  practical  matters,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  vii., 
it  seems  that  it  is  an  act  of  reason. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  ignorance  does  not  belong  to  the  will  but 
to  the  cognitive  power.     Now  there  is  an  ignorance  of  choice, 

158 


CHOICE  159 

as  is  stated  in  Ethic,  iii.     Therefore  it  seems  that  choice  does 
not  belong  to  the  will  but  to  the  reason. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.)  that 
choice  is  the  desire  of  things  in  our  own  power.  But  desire 
is  an  act  of  will.     Therefore  choice  is  too. 

/  answer  that,  The  word  choice  implies  something  belonging 
to  the  reason  or  intellect,  and  something  belonging  to  the 
will :  for  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  vi.)  that  choice  is  either 
intellect  influenced  by  appetite  or  appetite  influenced  by 
intellect.  Now  whenever  two  things  concur  to  make  one, 
one  of  them  is  formal  in  regard  to  the  other.  Hence  Gregory 
of  Nyssa  (Nemesius,  De  Nat.  Horn,  xxxiii.)  says  that  choice 
is  neither  desire  only,  nor  counsel  only,  but  a  combination  of 
the  two.  For  just  as  we  say  that  an  animal  is  composed  of  soul 
and  body,  and  that  it  is  neither  a  mere  body,  nor  a  mere  soul, 
but  both  ;  so  is  it  with  choice. 

Now  we  must  observe,  as  regards  the  acts  of  the  soul,  that 
an  act  belonging  essentially  to  some  power  or  habit,  receives 
a  form  or  species  from  a  higher  power  or  habit,  according  as 
an  inferior  is  ordained  by  a  superior:  for  if  a  man  were  to 
perform  an  act  of  fortitude  for  the  love  of  God,  that  act  is 
materially  an  act  of  fortitude,  but  formally,  an  act  of  charity. 
Now  it  is  evident  that,  in  a  sense,  reason  precedes  the  will 
and  ordains  its  act:  in  so  far  as  the  will  tends  to  its  object, 
according  to  the  order  of  reason,  since  the  apprehensive 
power  presents  the  object  to  the  appetite.  Accordingly, 
that  act  whereby  the  will  tends  to  something  proposed  to  it 
as  being  good,  through  being  ordained  to  the  end  by  the 
reason,  is  materially  an  act  of  the  will,  but  formally  an  act 
of  the  reason.  Now  in  suchlike  matters  the  substance  of  the 
act  is  as  the  matter  in  comparison  to  the  order  imposed  by 
the  higher  power.  Wherefore  choice  is  substantially  not  an 
act  of  the  reason  but  of  the  will:  for  choice  is  accomplished 
in  a  certain  movement  of  the  soul  towards  the  good  which 
is  chosen.  Consequently  it  is  evidently  an  act  of  the 
appetitive  power. 

Reply  Ob],  i.  Choice  implies  a  previous  comparison;  not 
as  though  it  consisted  in  the  comparison  itself. 


i6o  QUESTION  XIII 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  It  is  quite  true  that  it  is  for  the  reason  to 
draw  the  conclusion  of  a  practical  syllogism ;  and  it  is  called 
a  decision  or  judgment,  to  be  followed  by  choice.  And  for 
this  reason  the  conclusion  seems  to  belong  to  the  act  of 
choice,  as  to  that  which  results  from  it. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  In  speaking  of  ignorance  of  choice,  we  do  not 
mean  that  choice  is  a  sort  of  knowledge,  but  that  there  is 
ignorance  of  what  ought  to  be  chosen. 

Second  Article. 

whether  choice  is  within  the  competency 
of  irrational  animals  ? 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  irrational  animals  are  competent 
to  choose.  For  choice  is  the  desire  of  certain  things  on 
account  of  an  end,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iii.  But  irrational 
animals  desire  something  on  account  of  an  end :  since  they 
act  for  an  end,  and  from  desire.  Therefore  choice  is  in 
irrational  animals. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  very  word  electio  (choice)  seems  to 
signify  the  taking  of  something  in  preference  to  others. 
But  irrational  animals  take  something  in  preference  to 
others :  thus  we  can  easily  see  for  ourselves  that  a  sheep  will 
eat  one  grass  and  refuse  another.  Therefore  choice  is  in 
irrational  animals. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  according  to  Ethic,  vi.,  it  is  from  prudence 
that  a  man  makes  a  good  choice  of  means.  But  prudence  is 
within  the  competency  of  irrational  animals:  hence  it  is 
said  in  the  beginning  of  Metaph.  that  those  animals  which, 
like  hees,  cannot  hear  sounds,  are  prudent  hy  instinct.  We  see 
this  plainly,  in  wonderful  cases  of  sagacity  manifested  in  the 
works  of  various  animals,  such  as  bees,  spiders,  and  dogs. 
For  a  hound  in  following  a  stag,  on  coming  to  a  cross  road, 
tries  by  scent  whether  the  stag  has  passed  by  the  first  or  the 
second  road :  and  if  he  find  that  the  stag  has  not  passed  there, 
being  thus  assured,  takes  to  the  third  road  without  trying 
the  scent ;  as  though  he  were  reasoning  by  way  of  exclusion, 
arguing  that  the  stag  must  have  passed  by  this  way,  since 


CHOICE  i6i 

he  did  not  pass  by  the  others,  and  there  is  no  other  road. 
Therefore  it  seems  that  irrational  animals  are  competent  to 
choose. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat, 
Horn,  xxxiii.)  says  that  children  and  irrational  animals  act 
willingly  hut  not  from  choice.  Therefore  choice  is  not  in 
irrational  animals. 

/  answer  that,  Since  choice  is  the  taking  of  one  thing  in 
preference  to  another,  it  must  of  necessity  be  in  respect  of 
several  things  that  can  be  chosen.  Consequently  in  those 
things  which  are  altogether  determinate  to  one  there  is  no 
place  for  choice.  Now  the  difference  between  the  sensitive 
appetite  and  the  will  is  that,  as  stated  above  (Q.  I.  A.  2  ad  '^), 
the  sensitive  appetite  is  determinate  to  one  particular  thing, 
according  to  the  order  of  nature;  whereas  the  will,  although 
determinate  to  one  thing  in  general,  viz.,  the  good,  according 
to  the  order  of  nature,  is  nevertheless  indeterminate  in 
respect  of  particular  goods.  Consequently  choice  belongs 
properly  to  the  will,  and  not  to  the  sensitive  appetite  which 
is  all  that  irrational  animals  have.  Wherefore  irrational 
animals  are  not  competent  to  choose. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Not  every  desire  of  one  thing  on  account  of 
an  end  is  called  choice:  there  must  be  a  certain  discrimina- 
tion of  one  thing  from  another.  And  this  cannot  be  except 
when  the  appetite  can  be  moved  to  several  things. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  An  irrational  animal  takes  one  thing  in 
preference  to  another,  because  its  appetite  is  naturally 
determinate  to  that  thing.  Wherefore  as  soon  as  an  animal, 
whether  by  its  sense  or  by  its  imagination,  is  offered  some- 
thing to  which  its  appetite  is  naturally  inclined,  it  is  moved 
to  that  alone,  without  making  any  choice.  Just  as  fire  is 
moved  upwards  and  not  downwards,  without  its  making  any 
choice. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  in  Phys.  iii.  movement  is  the  act  of 
the  movable,  caused  by  a  mover.  Wherefore  the  power  of  the 
mover  appears  in  the  movement  of  that  which  it  moves. 
Accordingly,  in  all  things  moved  by  reason,  the  order  of 
reason  which  moves  them  is  evident,  although  the  things 

II.  I  II 


i62  QUESTION  XIII 

themselves  are  void  of  reason :  for  an  arrow  through  the 
motion  of  the  archer  goes  straight  towards  the  target,  as 
though  it  were  endowed  with  reason  to  direct  its  course. 
The  same  may  be  seen  in  the  movements  of  clocks  and  all 
engines  put  together  by  the  art  of  man.  Now  as  artificial 
things  are  in  comparison  to  human  art,  so  are  all  natural 
things  in  comparison  to  the  Divine  art.  And  accordingly 
order  is  to  be  seen  in  things  moved  by  nature,  just  as  in 
things  moved  by  reason,  as  is  stated  in  Phys.  ii.  And  thus 
it  is  that  in  the  works  of  irrational  animals  we  notice  certain 
marks  of  sagacity,  in  so  far  as  they  have  a  natural  inclination 
to  set  about  their  actions  in  a  most  orderly  manner,  through 
being  ordained  by  the  Supreme  art.  For  which  reason,  too, 
certain  animals  are  called  prudent  or  sagacious;  and  not 
because  they  reason  or  exercise  any  choice  about  things. 
This  is  clear  from  the  fact  that  all  that  share  in  one  nature, 
invariably  act  in  the  same  way. 

Third  Article. 

whether  choice  is  only  of  the  means,  or  sometimes 

also  of  the  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  choice  is  not  only  of  the  means. 
For  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  vi.)  that  virtue  makes  us 
choose  aright ;  hut  it  is  not  the  part  of  virtue,  hut  of  some  other 
power  to  direct  aright  those  things  which  are  to  he  done  for  its 
sake.  But  that  for  the  sake  of  which  something  is  done  is 
the  end.     Therefore  choice  is  of  the  end. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  choice  implies  preference  of  one  thing  to 
another.  But  just  as  there  can  be  preference  of  means,  so 
can  there  be  preference  of  ends.  Therefore  choice  can  be 
of  ends,  just  as  it  can  be  of  means. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.)  that 
volition  is  of  the  end,  hut  choice,  of  the  means. 

I  answer  that,  As  already  stated  (A.  i  ad  2),  choice  results 
from  the  decision  or  judgment  which  is,  as  it  were,  the  con- 
clusion of  a  practical  syllogism.     Hence  that  which  is  the 


CHOICE  163 

conclusion  of  a  practical  syllogism,  is  the  matter  of  choice. 
Now  in  practical  things  the  end  stands  in  the  position  of  a 
principle,  not  of  a  conclusion,  as  the  Philosopher  says 
(Phys.  ii.).  Wherefore  the  end,  as  such,  is  not  a  matter  of 
choice. 

But  just  as  in  speculative  knowledge  nothing  hinders  the 
principle  of  one  demonstration  or  of  one  science,  from  being 
the  conclusion  of  another  demonstration  or  science;  while 
the  first  indemonstrable  principle  cannot  be  the  conclusion 
of  any  demonstration  or  science;  so  too  that  which  is  the  end 
in  one  operation,  may  be  ordained  to  something  as  an  end. 
And  in  this  way  it  is  a  matter  of  choice.  Thus  in  the  work 
of  a  physician,  health  is  the  end :  wherefore  it  is  not  a  matter 
of  choice  for  a  physician,  but  a  matter  of  principle.  Now 
the  health  of  the  body  is  ordained  to  the  good  of  the  soul, 
consequently  with  one  who  has  charge  of  the  soul's  health, 
health  or  sickness  may  be  a  matter  of  choice ;  for  the  Apostle 
says  (2  Cor.  xii.  10) :  For  when  I  am  weak,  then  am  I  powerful. 
But  the  last  end  is  nowise  a  matter  of  choice. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  proper  ends  of  virtues  are  ordained  to 
Happiness  as  to  their  last  end.  And  thus  it  is  that  they  can 
be  a  matter  of  choice. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  As  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  5),  there  is  but 
one  last  end.  Accordingly  wherever  there  are  several  ends, 
they  can  be  the  subject  of  choice,  in  so  far  as  they  are 
ordained  to  a  further  end. 


Fourth  Article, 
whether  choice  is  of  those  things  only  that  are  done 

BY    US  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  choice  is  not  only  in  respect  of 
human  acts.  For  choice  regards  the  means.  Now,  not  only 
acts,  but  also  the  organs,  are  means  (Phys.  ii.).  Therefore 
choice  is  not  only  concerned  with  human  acts. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  action  is  distinct  from  contemplation. 
But  choice  has  a  place  even  in  contemplation;  in  so  far  as 


i64  QUESTION  XIII 

one  opinion  is  preferred  to  another.  Therefore  choice  is  not 
concerned  with  human  acts  alone. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  men  are  chosen  for  certain  posts,  whether 
secular  or  ecclesiastical,  by  those  who  exercise  no  action  in 
their  regard.  Therefore  choice  is  not  concerned  with  human 
acts  alone. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.)  that  no 
man  chooses  save  what  he  thinks  he  can  do  himself. 

I  answer  that,  Just  as  intention  regards  the  end,  so  does 
choice  regard  the  means.  Now  the  end  is  either  an  action 
or  a  thing.  And  when  the  end  is  a  thing,  some  human 
action  must  intervene;  either  in  so  far  as  man  produces  the 
thing  which  is  the  end,  as  the  physician  produces  health 
(wherefore  the  production  of  health  is  said  to  be  the  end  of 
the  physician) ;  or  in  so  far  as  man,  in  some  fashion,  uses  or 
enjoys  the  thing  which  is  the  end;  thus  for  the  miser,  money 
or  the  possession  of  money  is  the  end.  The  same  is  to  be 
said  of  the  means.  But  the  means  must  needs  be,  either  an 
action  or  a  thing,  through  some  action  intervening,  whereby 
man  either  makes  the  thing  which  is  the  means,  or  puts  it  to 
some  use.  And  thus  it  is  that  choice  is  always  in  regard  to 
human  acts. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  The  organs  are  ordained  to  the  end,  inas- 
much as  man  makes  use  of  them  for  the  sake  of  the  end. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  In  contemplation  itself  there  is  the  act  of 
the  intellect  assenting  to  this  or  that  opinion.  It  is  exterior 
action  that  is  put  in  contradistinction  to  contemplation. 

Reply  Obj.  3'.  When  a  man  chooses  someone  for  a  bishopric 
or  some  high  position  in  the  state,  he  chooses  to  name  that 
man  to  that  post.  Else,  if  he  had  no  right  to  act  in  the 
appointment  of  the  bishop  or  official,  he  would  have  no  right 
to  choose.  Likewise,  whenever  we  speak  of  one  thing  being 
chosen  in  preference  to  another,  it  is  in  conjunction  with 
some  action  of  the  chooser. 


CHOICE  165 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  choice  is  only  of  possible  things  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  choice  is  not  only  of  possible 
things.  For  choice  is  an  act  of  the  will,  as  stated  above 
(A.  i).  Now  there  is  a  willing  of  impossibilities  (Ethic,  iii.). 
Therefore  there  is  also  a  choice  of  impossibilities. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  choice  is  of  things  done  by  us,  as  stated 
above  (A.  4.)  Therefore  it  matters  not,  as  far  as  the  act  of 
choosing  is  concerned,  whether  one  choose  that  which  is 
impossible  in  itself,  or  that  which  is  impossible  to  the 
chooser.  Now  it  often  happens  that  we  are  unable  to  accom- 
plish what  we  choose;  so  that  this  proves  to  be  impossible 
to  us.     Therefore  choice  is  of  the  impossible. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  to  try  to  do  a  thing  is  to  choose  to  do  it. 
But  the  blessed  Benedict  says  {Regula  Ixviii.)  that  if  the 
superior  command  what  is  impossible,  it  should  be  attempted. 
Therefore  choice  can  be  of  the  impossible. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.)  that 
there  is  no  choice  of  impossibilities. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  4),  our  choice  is  always 
concerned  with  our  actions.  Now  whatever  is  done  by  us, 
is  possible  to  us.  Therefore  we  must  needs  say  that  choice 
is  only  of  possible  things. 

Moreover,  the  reason  for  choosing  a  thing  is  that  it  con- 
duces to  an  end.  But  what  is  impossible  cannot  conduce 
to  an  end.  A  sign  of  this  is  that  when  men  in  taking  counsel 
together  come  to  something  that  is  impossible  to  them, 
they  depart,  as  being  unable  to  proceed  with  the  business. 

Again,  this  is  evident  if  we  examine  the  process  of  the 
reason  that  precedes.  For  the  means,  which  are  the  object 
of  choice,  are  to  the  end,  as  the  conclusion  is  to  the  principle. 
Now  it  is  clear  that  an  impossible  conclusion  does  not  follow 
from  a  possible  principle.  Wherefore  an  end  cannot  be 
possible,  unless  the  means  be  possible.  Now  no  one  is 
moved  to  the  impossible.     Consequently  no  one  would  tend 


i66  QUESTION  XIII 

to  the  end,  save  for  the  fact  that  the  means  appear  to  be 
possible.  Therefore  the  impossible  is  not  the  object  of 
choice. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  will  stands  between  the  intellect  and 
the  external  action:  for  the  intellect  proposes  to  the  will  its 
object,  and  the  will  causes  the  external  action.  Hence  the 
principle  of  the  movement  in  the  will  is  to  be  found  in  the 
intellect,  which  apprehends  something  under  the  universal 
notion  of  good:  but  the  term  or  perfection  of  the  will's  act 
is  to  be  observed  in  its  relation  to  the  action  whereby  a  man 
tends  to  the  attainment  of  a  thing ;  for  the  movement  of  the 
will  is  from  the  soul  to  the  thing.  Consequently  the  perfect 
act  of  the  will  is  in  respect  of  something  that  is  good  for 
one  to  do.  Now  this  cannot  be  something  impossible. 
Wherefore  the  complete  act  of  the  will  is  only  in  respect  of 
what  is  possible  and  good  for  him  that  wills.  But  the  in- 
complete act  of  the  will  is  in  respect  of  the  impossible;  and 
by  some  is  called  velleity,  because,  to  wit,  one  would  will 
(vellet)  such  a  thing,  were  it  possible.  But  choice  is  an  act 
of  the  will,  fixed  on  something  to  be  done  by  the  chooser- 
And  therefore  it  is  by  no  means  of  anything  but  what  is 
possible. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Since  the  object  of  the  will  is  the  appre- 
hended good,  we  must  judge  of  the  object  of  the  will  accord- 
ing as  it  is  apprehended.  And  so,  just  as  sometimes  the  will 
tends  to  something  which  is  apprehended  as  good,  and  yet 
is  not  really  good;  so  is  choice  sometimes  made  of  something 
apprehended  as  possible  to  the  chooser,  and  yet  impossible 
to  him. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  reason  for  this  is  that  the  subject  should 
not  rely  on  his  own  judgment  to  decide  whether  a  certain 
thing  is  possible;  but  in  each  case  should  stand  by  his 
superior's  judgment. 


CHOICE  ^  167 


Sixth  Article, 
whether  man  chooses  of  necessity  or  freely  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  man  chooses  of  necessity.  For 
the  end  stands  in  relation  to  the  object  of  choice,  as  the 
principle  to  that  which  follows  from  the  principles,  as  de- 
clared in  Ethic,  vii.  But  conclusions  follow  of  necessity 
from  their  principles.  Therefore  man  is  moved  of  necessity 
from  (willing)  the  end  to  the  choice  (of  the  means). 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  as  stated  above  (A.  i  ad  2),  choice  follows 
the  reason's  judgment  of  what  is  to  be  done.  But  reason 
judges  of  necessity  about  some  things:  on  account  of  the 
necessity  of  the  premisses.  Therefore  it  seems  that  choice 
also  follows  of  necessity. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  two  things  are  absolutely  equal,  man 
is  not  moved  to  one  more  than  to  the  other;  thus  if  a  hungry 
man,  as  Plato  says  (cf.  De  Ccelo  ii.),  be  confronted  on  either 
side  with  two  portions  of  food  equally  appetizing  and  at  an 
equal  distance,  he  is  not  moved  towards  one  more  than  to 
the  other;  and  he  finds  the  reason  of  this  in  the  immobility 
of  the  earth  in  the  middle  of  the  world.  Now  much  less 
can  that  be  chosen  which  is  less  (eligible)  than  that  which  is 
equally  so.  Therefore  if  two  or  more  things  are  available, 
of  which  one  appears  to  be  more  (eligible),  it  is  impossible 
to  choose  any  of  the  others.  Therefore  that  which  appears 
to  hold  the  first  place  is  chosen  of  necessity.  But  every  act 
of  choosing  is  in  regard  to  something  that  seems  in  some  way 
better.     Therefore  every  choice  is  made  necessarily. 

On  the  contrary,  Choice  is  an  act  of  a  rational  power;  which 
according  to  the  Philosopher  (Metaph.  viii.)  stands  in  rela- 
tion to  opposites. 

I  answer  that,  Man  does  not  choose  of  necessity.  And 
this  is  because  that  which  is  possible  not  to  be,  is  not  of 
necessity.  Now  the  reason  why  it  is  possible  not  to  choose, 
or  to  choose,  may  be  gathered  from  a  twofold  power  in  man. 
For  man  can  will  and  not  will,  act  and  not  act;  again,  he  can 


i68  QUESTION  XIII 

will  this  or  that,  and  do  this  or  that.  The  reason  of  this 
is  seated  in  the  very  power  of  the  reason.  For  the  will  can 
tend  to  whatever  the  reason  can  apprehend  as  good.  Now 
the  reason  can  apprehend  as  good,  not  only  this,  viz.,  to  will 
or  to  act,  but  also  this,  viz.,  not  to  will  or  not  to  act.  Again, 
in  all  particular  goods,  the  reason  can  consider  an  aspect  of 
some  good,  and  the  lack  of  some  good,  which  has  the  aspect 
of  evil:  and  in  this  respect,  it  can  apprehend  any  single  one 
of  such  goods  as  to  be  chosen  or  to  be  avoided.  The  per- 
fect good  alone,  which  is  Happiness,  cannot  be  apprehended 
by  the  reason  as  an  evil,  or  as  lacking  in  any  way.  Conse- 
quently man  wills  Happiness  of  necessity,  nor  can  he  will 
not  to  be  happy,  or  to  be  unhappy.  Now  since  choice  is  not 
of  the  end,  but  of  the  means,  as  stated  above  (A.  3) ;  it  is  not 
of  the  perfect  good,  which  is  Happiness,  but  of  other  par- 
ticular goods.  Therefore  man  chooses  not  of  necessity,  but 
freely. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  conclusion  does  not  always  of  necessity 
follow  from  the  principles,  but  only  when  the  principles 
cannot  be  true  if  the  conclusion  is  not  true.  In  Hke  manner, 
the  end  does  not  always  necessitate  in  man  the  choosing  of 
the  means,  because  the  means  are  not  always  such  that  the 
end  cannot  be  gained  without  them;  or,  if  they  be  such,  they 
are  not  always  considered  in  that  light. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  reason's  decision  or  judgment  of  what 
is  to  be  done  is  about  things  that  are  contingent  and  possible 
to  us.  In  such  matters  the  conclusions  do  not  follow  of 
necessity  from  principles  that  are  absolutely  necessary,  but 
from  such  as  are  so  conditionally;  as,  for  instance.  If  he  runs, 
he  is  in  motion. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  If  two  things  be  proposed  as  equal  under 
one  aspect,  nothing  hinders  us  from  considering  in  one  of 
them  some  particular  point  of  superiority,  so  that  the  will 
has  a  bent  towards  that  one  rather  than  towards  the  other. 


QUESTION  XIV. 

OF  COUNSEL,  WHICH  PRECEDES  CHOICE. 

{In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  counsel ;  concerning  which  there  are 
six  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  counsel  is  an  inquiry  ? 

(2)  Whether  counsel  is   of    the  end    or    of    the    means  ? 

(3)  Whether    counsel    is    only   of    things    that   we    do  ? 

(4)  Whether  counsel  is  of  all  things  that  we  do  ?  (5)  Whether 
the  process  of  counsel  is  one  of  analysis  ?  (6)  Whether  the 
process  of  counsel  is  indefinite  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  counsel  is  an  inquiry  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  counsel  is  not  an  inquiry.  For 
Damascene  says  {De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that  counsel  is  an  act 
of  the  appetite.  But  inquiry  is  not  an  act  of  the  appetite. 
Therefore  counsel  is  not  an  inquiry. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  inquiry  is  a  discursive  act  of  the  intellect: 
for  which  reason  it  is  unbecoming  to  God,  Whose  knowledge 
is  not  discursive,  as  we  have  shown  in  the  First  Part 
(Q.  XIV.,  A.  7).  But  counsel  is  ascribed  to  God:  for  it  is 
written  (Eph.  i.  11)  that  He  worketh  all  things  according  to 
the  counsel  of  His  will.     Therefore  counsel  is  not  inquiry. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  inquiry  is  of  doubtful  matters.  But 
counsel  is  given  in  matters  that  are  certainly  good;  thus  the 
Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  vii.  25) :  Now  concerning  virgins  I  have 
no  commandment  of  the  Lord  :  hut  I  give  counsel.  Therefore, 
counsel  is  not  an  inquiry. 

169 


170  QUESTION  XIV 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  N3^ssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat. 
Horn,  xxxiv.)  says:  Every  counsel  is  an  inquiry  ;  but  not  every 
inquiry  is  a  counsel. 

I  answer  that,  Choice,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XIII. ,  K.  i  ad2\ 
A.  3),  follows  the  judgment  of  the  reason  about  what  is  to 
be  done.  Now  there  is  much  uncertainty  in  things  that 
have  to  be  done:  because  actions  are  concerned  with  con- 
tingent singulars,  which  by  reason  of  their  vicissitude,  are 
uncertain.  Now  in  things  doubtful  and  uncertain,  the 
reason  does  not  pronounce  judgment,  without  previous 
inquiry:  wherefore  the  reason  must  of  necessity  institute 
an  inquiry  before  deciding  on  the  objects  of  choice;  and  this 
inquiry  is  called  counsel.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says 
(Ethic,  iii.)  that  choice  is  the  desire  of  what  has  heen  already 
counselled. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  When  the  acts  of  two  powers  are  ordained 
to  one  another,  in  each  of  them  there  is  something  belonging 
to  the  other  power;  consequently  each  act  can  be  denomi- 
nated from  either  power.  Now  it  is  evident  that  the  act  of 
the  reason  giving  direction  as  to  the  means,  and  the  act  of  the 
will  tending  to  these  means  according  to  the  will's  direction, 
are  ordained  to  one  another.  Consequently  there  is  to  be 
found  something  of  the  reason,  viz.,  order,  in  that  act  of  the 
will,  which  is  choice:  and  in  counsel,  which  is  an  act  of 
reason,  something  of  the  will, — both  as  matter  (since  counsel 
is  of  what  man  wills  to  do), — and  as  motive  (because  it  is 
from  willing  the  end,  that  man  is  moved  to  take  counsel  in 
regard  to  the  means).  And  therefore,  just  as  the  Philoso- 
pher says  (Ethic  vi.)  that  choice  is  intellect  influenced  by 
appetite,  thus  pointing  out  that  both  concur  in  the  act  of 
choosing;  so  Damascene  says  (loc.  cit.)  that  counsel  is  appe- 
tite based  on  inquiry,  so  as  to  show  that  counsel  belongs,  in  a 
way,  both  to  the  will,  on  whose  behalf  and  by  whose  com- 
mand the  inquiry  is  made,  and  to  the  reason  that  executes 
the  inquiry. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  things  that  we  say  of  God  must  be 
understood  without  any  of  the  defects  which  are  to  be  found 
in  us :  thus  in  us  science  is  of  conclusions  derived  by  reason- 


COUNSEL  171 

ing  from  causes  to  effects:  but  science  when  said  of  God, 
means  sure  knowledge  of  all  effects  in  the  First  Cause,  with- 
out any  reasoning  process.  In  like  manner  we  ascribe 
counsel  to  God,  as  to  the  certainty  of  His  knowledge  or 
judgment,  which  certainty  in  us  arises  from  the  inquiry  of 
counsel.  But  such  inquiry  has  no  place  in  God;  wherefore 
in  this  respect  it  is  not  ascribed  to  God:  in  which  sense 
Damascene  says :  God  takes  not  counsel :  those  only  take  counsel 
who  lack  knowledge. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  There  is  no  reason  why  things  which  are  most 
certainly  good  in  the  opinion  of  wise  and  spiritual  men, 
should  not  be  certainly  good  in  the  opinion  of  many,  or  at 
least  of  carnal-minded  men.  Consequently  it  is  of  such 
things  that  we  take  counsel. 

Second  Article, 
whether  counsel  is  of  the  end,  or  only  of  the  means  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  counsel  is  not  only  of  the  means 
but  also  of  the  end.  For  whatever  is  doubtful,  can  be  the 
subject  of  inquiry.  Now  in  things  to  be  done  by  man  there 
happens  sometimes  a  doubt  as  to  the  end,  and  not  only  as 
to  the  means.  Since  therefore  inquiry  as  to  what  is  to  be 
done  is  counsel,  it  seems  that  counsel  can  be  of  the  end. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  matter  of  counsel  is  human  actions. 
But  some  human  actions  are  ends,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  i. 
Therefore  counsel  can  be  of  the  end. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat. 
Horn,  xxxiv.)  says  that  counsel  is  not  of  the  end,  hut  of  the 
means. 

I  answer  that,  The  end  is  the  principle  in  practical  matters: 
because  the  reason  of  the  means  is  to  be  found  in  the  end. 
Now  the  principle  cannot  be  called  in  question,  but  must  be 
presupposed  in  every  inquiry.  Since  therefore  counsel  is  an 
inquiry,  it  is  not  of  the  end,  but  only  of  the  means.  Never- 
theless it  happens  that  what  is  the  end  in  regard  to  some,  is 
ordained  to  something  else;  then  what  is  the  principle  of  one 


172  QUESTION  XIV 

demonstration,  is  the  conclusion  of  another:  and  conse- 
quently that  which  is  looked  upon  as  the  end  in  one  inquiry, 
may  be  looked  upon  as  the  means  in  another;  and  thus  it 
will  become  an  object  of  counsel. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  That  which  is  looked  upon  as  an  end,  is 
already  fixed:  consequently  as  long  as  there  is  any  doubt 
about  it,  it  is  not  looked  upon  as  an  end.  Wherefore  if 
counsel  is  taken  about  it,  it  will  be  counsel  not  about  the  end, 
but  about  the  means. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Counsel  is  about  operations,  in  so  far  as  they 
are  ordained  to  some  end.  Consequently  if  any  human  act 
be  an  end,  it  will  not,  as  such,  be  the  matter  of  counsel. 

Third  Article, 
whether  counsel  is  only  of  things  that  we  do  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  counsel  is  not  only  of  things 
that  we  do.  For  counsel  implies  some  kind  of  conference. 
But  it  is  possible  for  many  to  confer  about  things  that  are 
not  subject  to  movement,  and  are  not  the  result  of  our 
actions,  such  as  the  natures  of  various  things.  Therefore 
counsel  is  not  only  of  things  that  we  do. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  men  sometimes  seek  counsel  about  things 
that  are  laid  down  by  law;  hence  we  speak  of  counsel  at  law. 
And  yet  those  who  seek  counsel  thus,  have  nothing  to  do 
in  making  the  laws.  Therefore  counsel  is  not  only  of  things 
that  we  do. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  some  are  said  to  take  consultation  about 
future  events ;  which,  however,  are  not  in  our  power.  There- 
fore counsel  is  not  only  of  things  that  we  do. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  if  counsel  were  only  of  things  that  we  do, 
no  one  would  take  counsel  about  what  another  does.  But 
this  is  clearly  untrue.  Therefore  counsel  is  not  only  of 
things  that  we  do. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat. 
Horn,  xxxiv.)  says:  We  take  counsel  of  things  that  are  within 
our  competency  and  that  we  are  ahle  to  do. 


COUNSEL  173 

I  answer  that,  Counsel  properly  implies  a  conference  held 
between  several ;  the  very  word  {consilium)  denotes  this,  for 
it  means  a  sitting  together  (considium),  from  the  fact  that 
many  sit  together  in  order  to  confer  with  one  another.  Now 
we  must  take  note  that  in  contingent  particular  cases,  in 
order  that  anything  be  known  for  certain,  it  is  necessary  to 
take  several  conditions  or  circumstances  into  consideration, 
which  it  is  not  easy  for  one  to  consider,  but  are  con- 
sidered by  several  with  greater  certainty,  since  what  one 
takes  note  of,  escapes  the  notice  of  another;  whereas  in 
necessary  and  universal  things,  our  view  is  brought  to  bear 
on  matters  much  more  absolute  and  simple,  so  that  one  man 
by  himself  may  be  sufficient  to  consider  these  things.  Where- 
fore the  inquiry  of  counsel  is  concerned,  properly  speakings 
with  contingent  singulars.  Now  the  knowledge  of  the  truth 
in  such  matters  does  not  rank  so  high  as  to  be  desirable  of  it- 
self, as  is  the  knowledge  of  things  universal  and  necessary ; 
but  it  is  desired  as  being  useful  towards  action,  because 
actions  bear  on  things  singular  and  contingent.  Conse- 
quently, properly  speaking,  counsel  is  about  things  done 
by  us. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Counsel  implies  conference,  not  of  any  kind, 
but  about  what  is  to  be  done,  for  the  reason  given 
above. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  that  which  is  laid  down  by  the  law 
is  not  due  to  the  action  of  him  who  seeks  counsel,  neverthe- 
less it  directs  him  in  his  action :  since  the  mandate  of  the  law 
is  one  reason  for  doing  something. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Counsel  is  not  only  about  what  is  done,  but 
also  of  whatever  has  relation  to  what  is  done.  And  for  this 
reason  we  speak  of  consulting  about  future  events,  in  so  far 
as  man  is  induced  to  do  or  omit  something,  through  the 
knowledge  of  future  events. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  We  seek  counsel  about  the  actions  of  others, 
in  so  far  as  they  are,  in  some  way,  one  with  us;  either  by 
union  of  affection — thus  a  man  is  solicitous  about  what  con- 
cerns his  friend,  as  though  it  concerned  himself;  or  after  the 
manner  of  an  instrument,  for  the  principal  agent  and  the 


174  QUESTION  XIV 

instrument  are,  in  a  way,  one  cause,  since  one  acts  through 
the  other ;  thus  the  master  takes  counsel  about  what  he  would 
do  through  his  servant. 


Fourth  Article, 
whether  counsel  is  about  all  things  that  we  do  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  counsel  is  about  all  things  that 
we  have  to  do.  For  choice  is  the  desire  of  what  is  counselled 
as  stated  above  (A.  i) .  But  choice  is  about  all  things  that  we 
do.     Therefore  counsel  is  too. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  counsel  implies  the  reason's  inquiry.  But, 
whenever  we  do  not  act  through  the  impulse  of  passion,  we 
act  in  virtue  of  the  reason's  inquiry.  Therefore  there  is 
counsel  about  everything  that  we  do. 

Ob]\  3.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.)  that  if  it 
appears  that  something  can  be  done  by  more  means  than  one, 
we  take  counsel  by  inquiring  whereby  it  may  be  done  most 
easily  and  best ;  but  if  it  can  be  accomplished  by  one  means, 
how  it  can  be  done  by  this.  But  whatever  is  done,  is  done  by 
one  means  or  by  several.  Therefore  counsel  takes  place  in 
all  things  that  we  do. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat. 
Hom.  xxxiv.)  says  that  counsel  has  no  place  in  things  that  are 
done  according  to  science  or  art. 

I  answer  that.  Counsel  is  a  kind  of  inquiry,  as  stated  above 
(A.  i).  But  we  are  wont  to  inquire  about  things  that  admit 
of  doubt;  hence  the  process  of  inquiry,  which  is  called  an 
argument,  is  a  reason  that  certifies  to  something  that  admitted 
of  doubt  (Cicero, — Topic,  ad  Trebat.).  Now,  that  something 
in  relation  to  human  acts,  admit  of  no  doubt,  arises  from  a 
twofold  source.  First,  because  certain  determinate  ends 
are  gained  by  certain  determinate  means:  as  happens  in  the 
arts  which  are  governed  by  certain  fixed  rules  of  action; 
thus  a  writer  does  not  take  counsel  how  to  form  his  letters, 
for  this  is  determined  by  art. — Secondly,  from  the  fact  that 
it  little  matters  whether  it  is  done  this  or  that  way;  this 


COUNSEL  175 

occurs  in  minute  matters,  which  help  or  hinder  but  Httle 
towards  the  end  aimed  at ;  and  reason  looks  upon  small  things 
as  mere  nothings.  Consequently  there  are  two  things  of 
which  we  do  not  take  counsel,  although  they  conduce  to  the 
end,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.) :  namely,  minute 
things,  and  those  which  have  a  fixed  way  of  being  done,  as 
in  works  produced  by  art,  with  the  exception  of  those  arts 
that  admit  of  conjecture,  such  as  medicine,  commerce,  and 
the  like,  as  Gregory  of  Nyssa  says  (Nemesius, — loc,  cit.). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Choice  presupposes  counsel  by  reason  of  its 
judgment  or  decision.  Consequently  when  the  judgment  or 
decision  is  evident  without  inquiry,  there  is  no  need  for  the 
inquiry  of  counsel. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  In  matters  that  are  evident,  the  reason 
makes  no  inquiry,  but  judges  at  once.  Consequently  there 
is  no  need  of  counsel  in  all  that  is  done  by  reason. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  When  a  thing  can  be  accomplished  by  one 
means,  but  in  different  ways,  doubt  may  arise,  just  as  when 
it  can  be  accomplished  by  several  means:  hence  the  need 
of  counsel.  But  when  not  only  the  means,  but  also  the 
way  of  using  the  means,  is  fixed,  then  there  is  no  need  of 
counsel. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  the  process  of  counsel  is  one  of  analysis  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  process  of  counsel  is  not  one 
of  analysis.  For  counsel  is  about  things  that  we  do.  But 
the  process  of  our  actions  is  not  one  of  analysis,  but  rather 
one  of  synthesis,  viz.,  from  the  simple  to  the  composite. 
Therefore  counsel  does  not  always  proceed  by  way  of 
analysis. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  counsel  is  an  inquiry  of  the  reason.  But 
reason  proceeds  from  things  that  precede  to  things  that 
follow,  according  to  the  more  appropriate  order.  Since 
then,  the  past  precedes  the  present,  and  the  present  precedes 
the  future,  it  seems  that  in  taking  counsel  one  should  pro- 
ceed from  the  past  and  present  to  the  future:  which  is  not 


176  QUESTION  XIV 

an  analytical  process.  Therefore  the  process  of  counsel  is 
not  one  of  analysis. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  counsel  is  only  of  such  things  as  are  pos- 
sible to  us,  according  to  Ethic,  iii.  But  the  question  as  to 
whether  a  certain  thing  is  possible  to  us,  depends  on  what 
we  are  able  or  unable  to  do,  in  order  to  gain  such  and  such 
an  end.  Therefore  the  inquiry  of  counsel  should  begin 
from  things  present. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.)  that  he 
who  takes  counsel  seems  to  inquire  and  analyze. 

I  answer  that,  In  every  inquiry  one  must  begin  from  some 
principle.  And  if  this  principle  precedes  both  in  knowledge 
and  in  being,  the  process  is  not  analytic,  but  synthetic: 
because  to  proceed  from  cause  to  effect  is  to  proceed  syntheti- 
cally, since  causes  are  more  simple  than  effects.  But  if  that 
which  precedes  in  knowledge  comes  afterwards  into  being 
the  process  is  one  of  analysis,  as  when  our  judgment  deals 
with  effects,  which  by  analysis  we  trace  to  their  simple 
causes.  Now  the  principle  in  the  inquiry  of  counsel  is  the 
end,  which  precedes  indeed  in  intention,  but  comes  after- 
wards into  execution.  Hence  the  inquiry  of  counsel  must 
needs  be  one  of  analysis,  beginning,  that  is  to  say,  from 
that  which  is  intended  in  the  future,  and  continuing  until  it 
arrives  at  that  which  is  to  be  done  at  once. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Counsel  is  indeed  about  action.  But  actions 
take  their  reason  from  the  end;  and  consequently  the  order 
of  reasoning  about  actions  is  contrary  to  the  order  of  actions. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Reason  begins  with  that  which  is  first 
according  to  reason;  but  not  always  with  that  which  is  first 
in  point  of  time. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  We  should  not  want  to  know  whether  some- 
thing to  be  done  for  an  end  be  possible,  if  it  were  not  suitable 
for  gaining  that  end.  Hence  we  must  first  inquire  whether 
it  be  conducive  to  the  end,  before  considering  whether  it  be 
possible. 


COUNSEL  177 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  the  process  of  counsel  is  indefinite  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  process  of  counsel  is  in- 
definite. For  counsel  is  an  inquiry  about  the  particular 
things  with  which  action  is  concerned.  But  singulars  are 
infinite.     Therefore  the  process  of  counsel  is  indefinite. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  inquiry  of  counsel  has  to  consider  not 
only  what  is  to  be  done,  but  how  to  avoid  obstacles.  But 
every  human  action  can  be  hindered,  and  an  obstacle  can 
be  removed  by  some  human  reason.  Therefore  the  inquiry 
about  removing  obstacles  can  go  on  indefinitely. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  inquiry  of  demonstrative  science  does 
not  go  on  indefinitely,  because  one  can  come  to  principles 
that  are  self-evident,  which  are  absolutely  certain.  But 
suchlike  certainty  is  not  to  be  had  in  contingent  singulars, 
which  are  variable  and  uncertain.  Therefore  the  inquiry  of 
counsel  goes  on  indefinitely. 

On  the  contrary,  No  one  is  moved  to  that  which  he  cannot 
possibly  reach  (De  Ccelo  i.).  But  it  is  impossible  to  pass 
through  the  infinite.  If  therefore  the  inquiry  of  counsel  is 
infinite,  no  one  would  begin  to  take  counsel.  Which  is 
clearly  untrue. 

I  answer  that,  The  inquiry  of  counsel  is  actually  finite  on 
both  sides,  on  that  of  its  principle  and  on  that  of  its  term. 
For  a  twofold  principle  is  available  in  the  inquiry  of  counsel. 
One  is  proper  to  it,  and  belongs  to  the  very  genus  of  things 
pertaining  to  operation:  this  is  the  end,  which  is  not  the 
matter  of  counsel,  but  is  taken  for  granted  as  its  principle, 
as  stated  above  (A.  2).  The  other  principle  is  taken  from 
another  genus,  so  to  speak;  thus  in  demonstrative  sciences 
one  science  postulates  certain  things  from  another,  without 
inquiring  into  them.  Now  these  principles  which  are  taken 
for  granted  in  the  inquiry  of  counsel,  are  any  facts  received 
through  the  senses — for  instance,  that  this  is  bread  or  iron; 
and    also    any   general   statements   known   either   through 

II,  I  12 


178  QUESTION  XIV 

speculative  or  through  practical  science;  for  instance,  that 
adultery  is  forbidden  by  God,  or  that  man  cannot  live  with- 
out suitable  nourishment.  Of  such  things  counsel  makes  no 
inquiry. — But  the  term  of  inquiry  is  that  which  we  are  able  to 
do  at  once.  For  just  as  the  end  is  considered  in  the  light  of 
a  principle,  so  the  means  are  considered  in  the  light  of  a  con- 
clusion. Wherefore  that  which  presents  itself  as  to  be  done 
first,  holds  the  position  of  an  ultimate  conclusion,  whereat 
the  inquiry  comes  to  an  end. — Nothing  however  prevents 
counsel  from  being  infinite  potentially,  for  as  much  as  an 
infinite  number  of  things  may  present  themselves  to  be  in- 
quired into  by  means  of  counsel. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Singulars  are  infinite,  not  actually,  but  only 
potentially. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  human  action  can  be  hindered, 
the  hindrance  is  not  always  at  hand.  Consequently  it  is  not 
always  necessary  to  take  counsel  about  removing  the 
obstacle. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  In  contingent  singulars,  something  may  be 
taken  for  certain,  not  simply,  indeed,  but  for  the  time  being, 
and  as  far  as  it  concerns  the  work  to  be  done.  Thus  that 
Socrates  is  sitting  is  not  a  necessary  statement;  but  that  he 
is  sitting,  as  long  as  he  continues  to  sit,  is  necessary;  and 
this  can  be  taken  for  a  certain  fact. 


QUESTION  XV. 

OF  CONSENT,  WHICH   IS  AN  ACT  OF  THE  WILL  IN 
REGARD  TO  THE  MEANS. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  consent;  concerning  which  there  are 
four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  consent  is  an  act  of  the 
appetitive  or  of  the  apprehensive  power  ?  (2)  Whether  it 
is  becoming  to  irrational  animals  ?  (3)  Whether  it  is 
directed  to  the  end  or  to  the  means  ?  (4)  Whether  consent 
to  an  act  belongs  to  the  higher  part  of  the  soul  only  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  consent  is  an  act  of  the  appetitive  or  of 
the  apprehensive  power  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  consent  belongs  only  to  the 
appetitive  part  of  the  soul.  For  Augustine  (De  Trin.  xii.) 
ascribes  consent  to  the  higher  reason.  But  the  reason  is  an 
apprehensive  power.  Therefore  consent  belongs  to  an 
apprehensive  power. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  consent  is  co-sense.  But  sense  is  an  appre- 
hensive power.  Therefore  consent  is  the  act  of  an  appre- 
hensive power. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  just  as  assent  is  an  application  of  the 
intellect  to  something,  so  is  consent.  But  assent  belongs  to 
the  intellect,  which  is  an  apprehensive  power.  Therefore 
consent  also  belongs  to  an  apprehensive  power. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that 
if  a  man  judge  without  affection  for  that  of  which  he  judges, 

179 


i8o  QUESTION  XV 

there  is  no  sentence,    i.e.  consent.     But   affection   belongs 
to  the  appetitive  power.     Therefore  consent  does  also. 

I  answer  that,  Consent  implies  application  of  sense  to 
something.  Now  it  is  proper  to  sense  to  take  cognizance 
of  things  present;  for  the  imagination  apprehends  the 
similitude  of  corporeal  things,  even  in  the  absence  of  the 
things  of  which  they  bear  the  likeness;  while  the  intellect 
apprehends  universal  ideas,  which  it  can  apprehend  indiffer- 
ently, whether  the  singulars  be  present  or  absent.  And 
since  the  act  of  an  appetitive  power  is  a  kind  of  inclination 
to  the  thing  itself,  the  application  of  the  appetitive  power 
to  the  thing,  in  so  far  as  it  adheres  thereto,  takes  the  name 
of  sense,  by  a  kind  of  similitude,  seeking,  as  it  were,  a  closer 
acquaintance  with  the  thing,  in  so  far  as  it  takes  complacency 
in  it.  Hence  it  is  written  (Wisd.  i.  i) :  Think  of  (Sentite)  the 
Lord  in  goodness.  And  on  these  grounds  consent  is  an  act 
of  the  appetitive  power. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  As  stated  in  De  Anima  iii.,  the  will  is  in  the 
reason.  Hence,  when  Augustine  ascribes  consent  to  the 
reason,  he  takes  reason  as  including  the  will. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Sense,  properly  speaking,  belongs  to  the 
apprehensive  faculty;  but  by  way  of  similitude,  in  so  far  as 
it  implies  seeking  acquaintance,  it  belongs  to  the  appetitive 
power^,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Assentire  {to  assent)  is,  so  to  speak,  ad  aliud 
sentire  (to  feel  towards  something) ;  and  thus  it  implies  a  cer- 
tain distance  from  that  to  which  assent  is  given.  But  con- 
sentire  (to  consent)  is  to  feel  with,  and  this  implies  a  cer- 
tain union  to  the  object  of  consent.  Hence  the  will,  to 
which  it  belongs  to  tend  to  the  thing  itself,  is  more  properly 
said  to  consent:  whereas  the  intellect,  whose  act  does  not 
consist  in  a  movement  towards  the  thing,  but  rather  the 
reverse,  as  we  have  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XVI.,  A.  i; 
Q.  XXVII.,  A.  4;  Q.  LIX.,  A.  2),  is  more  properly  said  to 
assent:  although  one  word  is  wont  to  be  used  for  the  other.* 
We  may  also  say  that  the  intellect  assents,  in  so  far  as  it  is 
moved  by  the  will . 

*  In  Latin  rather  than  in  English. 


CONSENT  i8i 

Second  Article, 
whether  consent  is  becoming  to  irrational  animals  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  consent  is  becoming  to  irra- 
tional animals.  For  consent  implies  a  determination  of  the 
appetite  to  one  thing.  But  the  appetite  of  irrational  animals 
is  determinate  to  one  thing.  Therefore  consent  is  to  be 
found  in  irrational  animals. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  if  you  remove  what  is  first,  you  remove 
what  follows.  But  consent  precedes  the  accomplished  act. 
If  therefore  there  were  no  consent  in  irrational  animals,  there 
would  be  no  act  accomplished ;  which  is  clearly  false. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  men  are  sometimes  said  to  consent  to  do 
something,  through  some  passion;  desire,  for  instance,  or 
anger.  But  irrational  animals  act  through  passion.  There- 
fore they  consent. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that 
after  judging,  man  approves  and  embraces  the  judgment  of  his 
counselling,  and  this  is  called  the  sentence,  i.e.,  consent.  But 
counsel  is  not  in  irrational  animals.  Therefore  neither  is 
consent. 

/  answer  that,  Consent,  properly  speaking,  is  not  in 
irrational  animals.  The  reason  of  this  is  that  consent  im- 
plies an  application  of  the  appetitive  movement  to  some- 
thing as  to  be  done.  Now  to  apply  the  appetitive  move- 
ment to  the  doing  of  something,  belongs  to  the  subject  in 
whose  power  it  is  to  move  the  appetite :  thus  to  touch  a  stone 
is  an  action  suitable  to  a  stick,  but  to  apply  the  stick  so  that 
it  touch  the  stone,  belongs  to  one  who  has  the  power  of 
moving  the  stick.  But  irrational  animals  have  not  the 
command  of  the  appetitive  movement;  for  this  is  in  them 
through  natural  instinct.  Hence  in  the  irrational  animal 
there  is  indeed  the  movement  of  appetite,  but  it  does  not 
apply  that  movement  to  some  particular  thing.  And  hence 
it  is  that  the  irrational  animal  is  not  properly  said  to  con- 
sent: this  is  proper  to  the  rational  nature,  which  has  the 


i82  QUESTION  XV 

command  of  the  appetitive  movement,  and  is  able  to  apply 
or  not  apply  it  to  this  or  that  thing. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  In  irrational  animals  the  determination  of 
the  appetite  to  a  particular  thing  is  merely  passive:  whereas 
consent  implies  a  determination  of  the  appetite,  which  is 
active  rather  than  merely  passive. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  If  the  first  be  removed,  then  what  follows 
is  removed,  provided  that,  properly  speaking,  it  follow 
from  that  only.  But  if  something  can  follow  from  several 
things,  it  is  not  removed  by  the  fact  that  one  of  them  is 
removed;  thus  if  hardening  is  the  effect  of  heat  and  of  cold 
(since  bricks  are  hardened  by  fire,  and  frozen  water  is  hard- 
ened by  the  cold),  then  by  removing  heat  it  does  not  follow 
that  there  is  no  hardening.  Now  the  accomplishment  of  an 
act  follows  not  only  from  consent,  but  also  from  the  impulse 
of  the  appetite,  such  as  is  found  in  irrational  animals. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  man  who  acts  through  passion  is  able 
not  to  follow  the  passion:  whereas  irrational  animals  have 
not  that  power.     Hence  the  comparison  fails. 

Third  Article, 
whether  consent  is  directed  to  the  end  or  to  the 

MEANS  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  consent  is  directed  to  the  end. 
Because  that  on  account  of  which  a  thing  is  such  is  still  more 
such.  But  it  is  on  account  of  the  end  that  we  consent  to  the 
means.     Therefore  still  more  do  we  consent  to  the  end. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  act  of  the  intemperate  man  is  his 
end,  just  as  the  act  of  the  virtuous  man  is  his  end.  But  the 
intemperate  man  consents  to  his  own  act.  Therefore  con- 
sent can  be  directed  to  the  end. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  desire  of  the  means  is  choice,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XIII. ,  A.  i).  If  therefore  consent  were  only 
directed  to  the  means  it  would  nowise  differ  from  choice. 
And  this  is  proved  to  be  false  by  the  authority  of  Damascene 
who  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that  after  the  approval  which  he 


CONSENT  183 

calls  the  sentence,  comes  the  choice.  Therefore  consent  is  not 
only  directed  to  the  means. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  (ibid.)  that  the  sentence, 
i.e.,  the  consent,  takes  place  when  man  approves  and  embraces 
the  judgment  of  his  counsel.  But  counsel  is  only  about  the 
means.     Therefore  the  same  applies  to  consent. 

/  answer  that,  Consent  is  the  application  of  the  appetitive 
movement  to  something  that  is  already  in  the  power  of  him 
who  causes  the  application.  Now  the  order  of  action  is  this : 
First  there  is  the  apprehension  of  the  end ;  then  the  desire  of 
the  end;  then  the  counsel  about  the  means;  then  the  desire 
of  the  means.  Now  the  appetite  tends  to  the  last  end 
naturally :  wherefore  the  application  of  the  appetitive  move- 
ment to  the  apprehended  end  has  not  the  nature  of  consent, 
but  of  simple  volition.  But  as  to  those  things  which  come 
under  consideration  after  the  last  end,  in  so  far  as  they  are 
directed  to  the  end,  they  come  under  counsel:  and  so  con- 
sent can  be  applied  to  them,  in  so  far  as  the  appetitive 
movement  is  applied  to  the  judgment  resulting  from  counsel. 
But  the  appetitive  movement  to  the  end  is  not  applied  to 
counsel:  rather  is  counsel  applied  to  it,  because  counsel 
presupposes  the  desire  of  the  end.  On  the  other  hand,  the 
desire  of  the  means  presupposes  the  decision  of  counsel. 
And  therefore  the  application  of  the  appetitive  movement 
to  counsel's  decision  is  consent,  properly  speaking.  Conse- 
quently, since  counsel  is  only  about  the  means,  consent, 
properly  speaking,  is  of  nothing  else  but  the  means. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Just  as  the  knowledge  of  conclusions 
through  the  principles  is  science,  whereas  the  knowledge  of 
the  principles  is  not  science,  but  something  higher,  namely, 
understanding;  so  do  we  consent  to  the  means  on  account  of 
the  end,  in  respect  of  which  our  act  is  not  consent,  but  some- 
thing greater,  namely,  volition. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Delight  in  his  act,  rather  than  the  act  itself, 
is  the  end  of  the  intemperate  man,  and  for  sake  of  this 
delight  he  consents  to  that  act. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Choice  includes  something  that  consent  has 
not,  namely,  a  certain  relation  to  something  to  which  some- 


l84  •       QUESTION  XV 

thing  else  is  preferred :  and  therefore  after  consent  there  still 
remains  a  choice.  For  it  may  happen  that  by  aid  of  counsel 
several  means  have  been  found  conducive  to  the  end,  and 
through  each  of  these  meeting  with  approval,  consent  has 
been  given  to  each:  but  after  approving  of  many,  we  have 
given  our  preference  to  one  by  choosing  it.  But  if  only  one 
meets  with  approval,  then  consent  and  choice  do  not  differ 
in  reality,  but  only  in  our  way  of  looking  at  them;  so  that 
we  call  it  consent,  according  as  we  approve  of  doing  that 
thing;  but  choice,  according  as  we  prefer  it  to  those  that  do 
not  meet  with  our  approval. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  consent  to  the  act  belongs  only  to  the 
higher  part  of  the  soul  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  consent  to  the  act  does  not 
always  belong  to  the  higher  reason.  For  delight  follows 
action,  and  perfects  it,  just  as  beauty  perfects  youth  *  [Ethic,  x.). 
But  consent  to  delight  belongs  to  the  lower  reason,  as 
Augustine  says  [De  Trin.  xii.).  Therefore  consent  to  the 
act  does  not  belong  only  to  the  higher  reason. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  an  act  to  which  we  consent  is  said  to  be 
voluntary.  But  it  belongs  to  many  powers  to  produce 
voluntary  acts.  Therefore  the  higher  reason  is  not  alone  in 
consenting  to  the  act. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  higher  reason  is  that  which  is  intent  on 
the  contemplation  and  consultation  of  things  eternal,  as  Augus- 
tine says  (De  Trin.  xii.).  But  man  often  consents  to  an  act 
not  for  eternal,  but  for  temporal  reasons,  or  even  on  account 
of  some  passion  of  the  soul.  Therefore  consent  to  an  act 
does  not  belong  to  the  higher  reason  alone. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  xii.):  It  is  im- 
possible for  man  to  make  up  his  mind  to  commit  a  sin,  unless 
that  mental  faculty ,  which  has  the  sovereign  power  of  urging  to, 

*  olov  Tols  aKixaioLs  rj  copa; — as  youtliful  vigour  perfects  a  man  in  his 
prime. 


CONSENT  185 

oy  restraining  from,  act,  yield  to  the  evil  deed  and  become  its 
slave. 

I  answer  that,  The  final  decision  belongs  to  him  who  holds 
the  highest  place,  and  to  whom  it  belongs  to  judge  of  the 
others;  for  as  long  as  judgment  about  some  matter  remains 
to  be  pronounced,  the  final  decision  has  not  been  given. 
Now  it  is  evident  that  it  belongs  to  the  Higher  reason  to 
judge  of  all :  since  it  is  by  the  reason  that  we  judge  of  sensible 
things;  and  of  things  pertaining  to  human  principles  we 
judge  according  to  Divine  principles,  which  is  the  function 
of  the  higher  reason.  Wherefore  as  long  as  a  man  is  un- 
certain whether  he  resists  or  not,  according  to  Divine 
principles,  no  judgment  of  the  reason  can  be  considered  in 
the  light  of  a  final  decision.  Now  the  final  decision  of  what 
is  to  be  done  is  consent  to  the  act.  Therefore  consent  to 
the  act  belongs  to  the  higher  reason;  but  in  that  sense  in 
which  the  reason  includes  the  will,  as  stated  above  (A.  ladi.) 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Consent  to  delight  in  the  work  done  belongs 
to  the  higher  reason,  as  also  does  consent  to  the  work;  but 
consent  to  delight  in  thought  belongs  to  the  lower  reason, 
just  as  to  the  lower  reason  it  belongs  to  think.  Neverthe- 
less the  higher  reason  exercises  judgment  on  the  fact  of 
thinking  or  not  thinking,  considered  as  an  action ;  and  in  like 
manner  on  the  delight  that  results.  But  in  so  far  as  the 
act  of  thinking  is  considered  as  ordained  to  a  further  act, 
it  belongs  to  the  lower  reason.  For  that  which  is  ordained 
to  something  else,  belongs  to  a  lower  act  or  power  than  does 
the  end  to  which  it  is  ordained:  hence  the  act  which  is 
concerned  with  the  end  is  called  the  master  or  principal  act. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Since  actions  are  called  voluntary  from  the 
fact  that  we  consent  to  them,  it  does  not  follow  that  consent 
is  an  act  of  each  power,  but  of  the  will  which  is  in  the  reason, 
as  stated  above  (A.  1  ad  t),  and  from  which  the  voluntary 
act  is  named. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  higher  reason  is  said  to  consent  not 
only  because  it  always  moves  to  act,  according  to  the  eternal 
reasons;  but  also  because  it  fails  to  dissent  according  to 
those  same  reasons. 


QUESTION  XVI. 

OF  USE,  WHICH  IS  AN  ACT  OF  THE  WILL  IN 
REGARD  TO  THE  MEANS. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  use;  concerning  which  there  are  four 
points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  use  is  an  act  of  the  will  ? 

(2)  Whether     it     is     becoming     to     irrational     animals  ? 

(3)  Whether  it  regards  the  means  only,  or  the  end  also  ? 

(4)  Of  the  relation  of  use  to  choice. 

First  Article, 
whether  use  is  an  act  of  the  will  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  use  is  not  an  act  of  the  will. 
For  Augustine  says  {De  Doctr.  Christ,  i.)  that  to  use  is  to  refer 
that  which  is  the  object  of  use  to  the  obtaining  of  something  else. 
But  to  refer  something  to  another  is  an  act  of  the  reason  to 
which  it  belongs  to  compare  and  to  direct.  Therefore  use 
is  an  act  of  the  reason  and  not  of  the  will. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.) 
that  man  goes  forward  to  the  operation,  and  this  is  called 
impulse  ;  then  he  makes  use  (of  the  powers)  and  this  is  called 
use.  But  operation  belongs  to  the  executive  power ;  and  the 
act  of  the  will  does  not  follow  the  act  of  the  executive  power, 
on  the  contrary  execution  comes  last.  Therefore  use  is  not 
an  act  of  the  will. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  (Qq.  83) :  All  things  that 
were  made  were  made  for  man's  use,  because  reason  with  which 
man  is  endowed  uses  all  things  by  its  judgment  of  them.  But 
judgment  of  things  created  by  God  belongs  to  the  specula- 

t86 


USE  187 

tive  reason;  which  seems  to  be  altogether  distinct  from  the 
will,  which  is  the  principle  of  human  acts.  Therefore  use  is 
not  an  act  of  the  will. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  x.) :  To  use  is  to 
apply  something  to  the  purpose  of  the  will. 

I  answer  that,  The  use  of  a  thing  implies  the  application  of 
that  thing  to  an  operation :  hence  the  operation  to  which  we 
apply  a  thing  is  called  its  use;  thus  the  use  of  a  horse  is  to 
ride,  and  the  use  of  a  stick  is  to  strike.  Now  we  apply  to  an 
operation  not  only  the  interior  principles  of  action,  viz.,  the 
powers  of  the  soul  or  the  members  of  the  body ;  as  the  intel- 
lect, to  understand;  and  the  eye,  to  see;  but  also  external 
things,  as  a  stick,  to  strike.  But  it  is  evident  that  we  do 
not  apply  external  things  to  an  operation  save  through  the 
interior  principles,  which  are  either  the  powers  of  the  soul, 
or  the  habits  of  those  powers,  or  the  organs  which  are  parts 
of  the  body.  Now  it  has  been  shown  above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  i) 
that  it  is  the  will  which  moves  the  soul's  powers  to  their 
acts,  and  this  is  to  apply  them  to  operation.  Hence  it  is 
evident  that  first  and  principally  use  belongs  to  the  will  as 
first  mover;  to  the  reason,  as  directing;  and  to  the  other 
powers  as  executing  the  operation,  which  powers  are  com- 
pared to  the  will  which  applies  them  to  act,  as  the  instru- 
ments are  compared  to  the  principle  agent.  Now  action  is 
properly  ascribed,  not  to  the  instrument,  but  to  the  principal 
agent,  as  building  is  ascribed  to  the  builder,  but  not  to  his 
tools.  Hence  it  is  evident  that  use  is,  properly  speaking,  an 
act  of  the  will. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Reason  does  indeed  refer  one  thing  to  an- 
other; but  the  will  tends  to  that  which  is  referred  by  the 
reason  to  something  else.  And  in  this  sense  to  use  is  to 
refer  one  thing  to  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Damascene  is  speaking  of  use  in  so  far  as  it 
belongs  to  the  executive  powers. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Even  the  speculative  reason  is  applied  by 
the  will  to  the  act  of  understanding  or  judging.  Conse- 
quently the  speculative  reason  is  said  to  use,  in  so  far  as  it 
is  moved  by  the  will,  in  the  same  way  as  the  other  powers. 


i88  QUESTION  XVI 

Second  Article, 
whether  use  is  becoming  to  irrational  animals  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  :■ — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  use  is  becoming  to  irrational 
animals.  For  it  is  better  to  enjoy  than  to  use,  because,  as 
Augustine  says  {De  Trin.  x.) :  We  use  things  by  referring  them 
to  something  else  which  we  are  to  enjoy.  But  enjoyment  is 
becoming  to  irrational  animals,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XL,  A.  2). 
Much  more,  therefore,  is  it  becoming  for  them  to  use. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  to  apply  the  members  to  action  is  to  use 
them.  But  irrational  animals  apply  their  members  to 
action;  for  instance,  their  feet,  to  walk;  their  horns,  to 
strike.  Therefore  it  is  becoming  for  irrational  animals  to 
use. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Qq.  83):  None  but  a 
rational  animal  can  make  use  of  a  thing. 

I  answer  that,  as  stated  above  (A.  i),  to  use  is  to  apply 
an  active  principle  to  action :  thus  to  consent  is  to  apply  the 
appetitive  movement  to  the  desire  of  something,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XV.,  AA.  i,  2,  3).  Now  he  alone  who  has  the 
disposal  of  a  thing,  can  apply  it  to  something  else;  and  this 
belongs  to  him  alone  who  knows  how  to  refer  it  to  something 
else,  which  is  an  act  of  the  reason.  And  therefore  none  but 
a  rational  animal  consents  and  uses. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  To  enjoy  implies  the  absolute  movement  of 
the  appetite  to  the  appetible:  whereas  to  use  implies  a 
movement  of  the  appetite  to  something  as  directed  to  some- 
thing else.  If  therefore  we  compare  use  and  enjoyment  in 
respect  of  their  objects,  enjoyment  is  better  than  use;  be- 
cause that  which  is  appetible  absolutely  is  better  than  that 
which  is  appetible  only  as  directed  to  something  else.  But 
if  we  compare  them  in  respect  of  the  apprehensive  power 
that  precedes  them,  greater  excellence  is  required  on  the 
part  of  use:  because  to  direct  one  thing  to  another  is  an  act 
of  reason;  whereas  to  apprehend  something  absolutely  is 
within  the  competency  even  of  sense. 


USE  189 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Animals  by  means  of  their  members  do 
something  from  natural  instinct;  not  through  knowing  the 
relation  of  their  members  to  these  operations.  Wherefore, 
properly  speaking,  they  do  not  apply  their  members  to 
action,  nor  do  they  use  them. 

Third  Article, 
whether  use  regards  also  the  last  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  use  can  regard  also  the  last  end. 
For  Augustine  says  [De  Trin.  x.) :  Whoever  enjoys,  uses.  But 
man  enjoys  the  last  end.     Therefore  he  uses  the  last  end. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  to  use  is  to  apply  something  to  the  purpose 
of  the  will  (ibid).  But  the  last  end,  more  than  anything 
else,  is  the  object  of  the  will's  application.  Therefore  it  can 
be  the  object  of  use. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Hilary  says  (De  Trin.  ii.)  that  Eternity  is 
in  the  Father,  Likeness  in  the  Image,  i.e.,  in  the  Son,  Use  in 
the  Gift,  i.e.,  in  the  Holy  Ghost.  But  the  Holy  Ghost,  since 
He  is  God,  is  the  last  end.  Therefore  the  last  end  can  be  the 
object  of  use. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Qq.  83) :  No  one  rightly 
uses  God,  but  he  enjoys  Him.  But  God  alone  is  the  last  end. 
Therefore  we  cannot  use  the  last  end. 

I  answer  that.  Use,  as  stated  above  (A.  i),  implies  the  ap- 
plication of  one  thing  to  another.  Now  that  which  is  applied 
to  another  is  regarded  in  the  light  of  means  to  an  end;  and 
consequently  use  always  regards  the  means.  For  this 
reason  things  that  are  adapted  to  a  certain  end  are  said  to  be 
useful ;  in  fact  their  very  usefulness  is  sometimes  called  use. 

It  must,  however,  be  observed  that  the  last  end  may 
be  taken  in  two  ways :  first,  simply ;  secondly,  in  respect  of 
an  individual.  For  since  the  end,  as  stated  above  (Q.  I., 
A.  8;  Q.  II.,  A.  7),  signifies  sometimes  the  thing  itself,  and 
sometimes  the  attainment  or  possession  of  that  thing  (thus 
the  miser's  end  is  either  money  or  the  possession  of  it) ;  it  is 
evident  that,  simply  speaking,  the  last  end  is  the  thing 


igo  QUESTION  XVI 

itself;  for  the  possession  of  money  is  good  only  inasmuch  as 
there  is  some  good  in  money.  But  in  regard  to  the  individual, 
the  obtaining  of  money  is  the  last  end ;  for  the  miser  would 
not  seek  for  money,  save  that  he  might  have  it.  Therefore, 
simply  and  properly  speaking,  a  man  enjoys  money,  because 
he  places  his  last  end  therein;  but  in  so  far  as  he  seeks  to 
possess  it,  he  is  said  to  use  it. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Augustine  is  speaking  of  use  in  general,  in  so 
far  as  it  implies  the  relation  of  an  end  to  the  enjoyment 
which  a  man  seeks  in  that  end. 

Refly  Ohj.  2.  The  end  is  applied  to  the  purpose  of  the  will, 
that  the  will  may  find  rest  in  it.  Consequently  this  rest  in 
the  end,  which  is  the  enjoyment  thereof,  is  in  this  sense 
called  use  of  the  end.  But  the  means  are  applied  to  the 
will's  purpose,  not  only  in  being  used  as  means,  but  as  or- 
dained to  something  else  in  which  the  will  finds  rest. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  words  of  Hilary  refer  to  use  as  applic- 
able to  rest  in  the  last  end ;  just  as,  speaking  in  a  general 
sense,  one  may  be  said  to  use  the  end  for  the  purpose  of 
attaining  it,  as  stated  above.  Hence  Augustine  says  {De 
Trin.  vi.)  that  this  love,  delight,  felicity,  or  happiness,  is  called 
use  hy  him. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  use  precedes  choice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  use  precedes  choice.  For 
nothing  follows  after  choice,  except  execution.  But  use, 
since  it  belongs  to  the  will,  precedes  execution.  Therefore 
it  precedes  choice  also. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  absolute  precedes  the  relative.  There- 
fore the  less  relative  precedes  the  more  relative.  But 
choice  implies  two  relations:  one,  of  the  thing  chosen,  in 
relation  to  the  end;  the  other,  of  the  thing  chosen,  in  respect 
of  that  to  which  it  is  preferred;  whereas  use  implies  relation 
to  the  end  only.     Therefore  use  precedes  choice. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  will  uses  the  other  powers  in  so  far 
as  it  moves  them.     But  the  will  moves  itself  too,  as  stated 


USE  191 

above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  3).  Therefore  it  uses  itself,  by  applying 
itself  to  act.  But  it  does  this  when  it  consents.  Therefore 
there  is  use  in  consent.  But  consent  precedes  choice,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  XV.,  A.  3  ad  3).  Therefore  use  does 
also. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod,  ii.)  that 
the  will  after  choosing  has  an  impulse  to  the  operation,  and 
afterwards  it  uses  (the  powers).     Therefore  use  follows  choice. 

I  answer  that.  The  will  has  a  twofold  relation  to  the  thing 
willed.  One,  according  as  the  thing  willed  is,  in  a  way,  in 
the  willing  subject,  by  a  kind  of  proportion  or  order  to  the 
thing  willed.  Wherefore  those  things  that  are  naturally 
proportionate  to  a  certain  end,  are  said  to  desire  that  end 
naturally. — Yet  to  have  an  end  thus  is  to  have  it  imperfectly. 
Now  every  imperfect  thing  tends  to  perfection.  And  there- 
fore both  the  natural  and  the  voluntary  appetite  tends  to 
have  the  end  in  reality ;  and  this  is  to  have  it  perfectly.  This 
is  the  second  relation  of  the  will  to  the  thing  willed. 

Now  the  thing  willed  is  not  only  the  end,  but  also  the 
means.  And  the  last  act  that  belorgs  to  the  first  relation 
of  the  will  to  the  means,  is  choice;  for  there  the  will  becomes 
fully  proportionate,  by  willing  the  means  fully.  Use,  on  the 
other  hand,  belongs  to  the  second  relation  of  the  will,  in 
respect  of  which  it  tends  to  the  realization  of  the  thing  willed. 
Wherefore  it  is  evident  that  use  follows  choice ;  provided  that 
by  use  we  mean  the  will's  use  of  the  executive  power  in 
moving  it.  But  since  the  will,  in  a  way,  moves  the  reason 
also,  and  uses  it,  we  may  take  the  use  of  the  means,  as  con- 
sisting in  the  consideration  of  the  reason,  whereby  it  refers 
the  means  to  the  end.     In  this  sense  use  precedes  choice. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  motion  of  the  will  to  the  execution  of  the 
work,  precedes  execution,  but  follows  choice.  And  so, 
since  use  belongs  to  that  very  motion  of  the  will,  it  stands 
between  choice  and  execution. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  What  is  essentially  relative  is  after  the 
absolute;  but  the  thing  to  which  relation  is  referred  need 
not  come  after.  Indeed,  the  more  a  cause  precedes,  the  more 
numerous  the  effects  to  which  it  has  relation. 


192  QUESTION  XVI 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Choice  precedes  use,  if  they  be  referred  to 
the  same  object.  But  nothing  hinders  the  use  of  one  thing 
preceding  the  choice  of  another.  And  since  the  acts  of  the 
will  react  on  one  another,  in  each  act  of  the  will  we  can  find 
both  consent  and  choice  and  use;  so  that  we  may  say  that 
the  will  consents  to  choose,  and  consents  to  consent,  and 
uses  itself  in  consenting  and  choosing.  And  such  acts  as  are 
ordained  to  that  which  precedes,  precede  also. 


QUESTION  XVII. 

OF  THE  ACTS  COMMANDED  BY  THE  WILL. 

{In  Nine  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  acts  commanded  by  the  will ; 
under  which  head  there  are  nine  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  command  is  an  act  of  the  will  or  of  the  reason  ? 

(2)  Whether    command    belongs    to    irrational    animals  ? 

(3)  Of  the  order  between  command  and  use.  (4)  Whether 
command  and  the  commanded  act  are  one  act  or  distinct  ? 
(5)  Whether  the  act  of  the  will  is  commanded  ?  (6)  Whether 
the  act  of  the  reason  is  commanded  ?  (7)  Whether  the  act 
of  th^  sensitive  appetite  is  commanded  ?  (8)  Whether  the 
act  of  the  vegetal  soul  is  commanded  ?  (9)  Whether  the  acts 
of  the  external  members  are  commanded  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  command  is  an  act  of  the  reason  or  of  the 

WILL  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  command  is  not  an  act  of  the 
reason  but  of  the  will.  For  command  is  a  kind  of  motion; 
because  Avicenna  says  that  a  mover  is  fourfold,  by  per- 
fecting, by  disposing,  by  commanding,  and  by  counselling. 
But  it  belongs  to  the  will  to  move  all  the  other  powers  of  the 
soul,  as  stated  above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  i).  Therefore  command 
is  an  act  of  the  will. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  just  as  to  be  commanded  belongs  to  that 
which  is  subject,  so,  seemingly,  to  command  belongs  to  that 
which  is  most  free.  But  the  root  of  liberty  is  especially  in 
the  will.     Therefore  to  command  belongs  to  the  will. 

II.  I  193  13 


194  QUESTION  XVII 

Obj.  3.  Further,  command  is  followed  at  once  by  act.  But 
the  act  of  the  reason  is  not  followed  at  once  by  act :  for  he  who 
judges  that  a  thing  should  be  done,  does  not  do  it  at  once. 
Therefore  command  is  not  an  act  of  the  reason,  but  of  the  will. 
On  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat. 
Horn,  xvi.)  and  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  i.)  say  that  the  appe- 
tite obeys  reason.  Therefore  command  is  an  act  of  the 
reason. 

/  answer  that,  Command  is  an  act  of  the  reason,  presup- 
posing, however,  an  act  of  the  will.  In  proof  of  this,  we  must 
take  note  that,  since  the  acts  of  the  reason  and  of  the  will 
can  be  brought  to  bear  on  one  another,  in  so  far  as  the 
reason  reasons  about  willing,  and  the  will  wills  to  reason,  the 
result  is  that  the  act  of  the  reason  precedes  the  act  of  the 
will,  and  conversely.  And  since  the  power  of  the  preceding 
act  continues  in  the  act  that  follows,  it  happens  sometimes 
that  there  is  an  act  of  the  will  in  so  far  as  it  retains  in  itself 
something  of  an  act  of  the  reason,  as  we  have  stated  in  refer- 
ence to  use  and  choice;  and  conversely,  that  there  is  an  act 
of  the  reason  in  so  far  as  it  retains  in  itself  something  of  an 
act  of  the  will. 

Now,  command  is  essentially  indeed  an  act  of  the  reason: 
for  the  commander  orders  the  one  commanded  to  do  some- 
thing, by  way  of  intimation  or  declaration;  and  to  order 
thus  by  intimating  or  declaring  is  an  act  of  the  reason.     Now 
the  reason  can  intimate  or  declare  something  in  two  ways. 
First,  absolutely :  and  this  intimation  is  expressed  by  a  verb 
in  the  indicative  mood,  as  when  one  person  says  to  another: 
This  is  what  you  should  do.     Sometimes,  however,  the  reason 
intimates  something  to  a  man  by  moving  him  thereto ;  and 
this  intimation  is  expressed  by  a  verb  in  the  imperative 
mood;  as  when  it  is  said  to  someone:  Do  this.     Now  the  first 
mover,  among  the  powers  of  the  soul,  to  the  doing  of  an 
act  is  the  will,  as  stated  above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  i).     Since,  there- 
fore, the  second  mover  does  not  move,  save  in  virtue  of  the 
first  mover,  it  follows  that  the  very  fact  that  the   reason 
moves  by  commanding,  is  due  to  the  power  of  the  will.  Con- 
sequently it  follows  that  command  is  an  act  of  the  reason, 


COMMANDED  ACTS  195 

presupposing  an  act  of  the  will,  in  virtue  of  which  the 
reason,  by  its  command,  moves  (the  power)  to  the  execution 
of  the  act. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  To  command  is  to  move,  not  anyhow,  but  by 
intimating  and  declaring  to  another;  and  this  is  an  act  of 
the  reason. 

Reply  Ohj,  2.  The  root  of  liberty  is  the  will  as  the  subject 
thereof;  but  it  is  the  reason  as  its  cause.  For  the  will  can 
tend  freely  towards  various  objects,  precisely  because  the 
reason  can  have  various  perceptions  of  good.  Hence  philo- 
sophers define  the  free-will  as  being  a  free  judgment  arising 
from  reason,  implying  that  reason  is  the  root  of  liberty. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  argument  proves  that  command  is  an 
act  of  reason  not  absolutely,  but  with  a  kind  of  motion,  as 
stated  above. 

Second  Article, 
whether  command  belongs  to  irrational  animals  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  command  belongs  to  irrational 
animals.  Because,  according  to  Avicenna,  the  power  that 
commands  movement  is  the  appetite ;  and  the  power  that 
executes  movement  is  in  the  muscles  and  nerves.  But  both 
powers  are  in  irrational  animals.  Therefore  command  is  to 
be  found  in  irrational  animals. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  condition  of  a  slave  is  that  of  one  who 
receives  commands.  But  the  body  is  compared  to  the  soul, 
as  a  slave  to  his  master,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (Polit.  i.). 
Therefore  the  body  is  commanded  by  the  soul,  even  in 
irrational  animals,  since  they  are  composed  of  soul  and  body. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  by  commanding,  man  has  an  impulse 
towards  an  action.  But  impulse  to  action  is  to  be  found  in 
irrational  animals,  as  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.). 
Therefore  command  is  to  be  found  in  irrational  animals. 

On  the  contrary,  Command  is  an  act  of  reason,  as  stated 
above  (A.  i).  But  in  irrational  animals  there  is  no  reason. 
Neither,  therefore,  is  there  command. 

/  answer  that,  To  command  is  nothing  else  than  to  direct 


196  QUESTION  XVII 

someone  to  do  something,  by  a  certain  motion  of  intimation. 
Now  to  direct  is  the  proper  act  of  the  reason.  Wherefore  it 
is  impossible  that  irrational  animals  should  command  in  any 
way,  since  they  are  devoid  of  reason. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  appetitive  power  is  said  to  command 
movement,  in  so  far  as  it  moves  the  commanding  reason. 
But  this  is  only  in  man.  In  irrational  animals  the  appe- 
titive power  is  not,  properly  speaking,  a  commanding 
faculty,  unless  command  be  taken  loosely  for  motion. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  body  of  the  irrational  animal  is  com- 
petent to  obey;  but  its  soul  is  not  competent  to  command, 
because  it  is  not  competent  to  direct.  Consequently  there 
is  no  ratio  there  of  commander  and  commanded;  but  only 
of  mover  and  moved. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Impulse  to  action  is  in  irrational  animals 
otherwise  than  in  man.  For  the  impulse  of  man  to  action 
arises  from  the  directing  reason;  wherefore  his  impulse  is 
one  of  command.  On  the  other  hand,  the  impulse  of  the 
irrational  animal  arises  from  natural  instinct;  because  as 
soon  as  they  apprehend  the  fitting  or  the  unfitting,  their 
appetite  is  moved  naturally  to  pursue  or  to  avoid.  Where- 
fore they  are  directed  by  another  to  act:  and  they  them- 
selves do  not  direct  themselves  to  act.  Consequently  in 
them  is  impulse  but  not  command. 

Third  Article, 
whether  use  precedes  command  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  use  precedes  command.  For 
command  is  an  act  of  the  reason  presupposing  an  act  of  the 
will,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  But,  as  we  have  already  shown 
(Q.  XVI.,  A.  i),  use  is  an  act  of  the  will.  Therefore  use  pre- 
cedes command. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  command  is  one  of  those  things  that  are 
ordained  to  the  end.  But  use  is  of  those  things  that  are 
ordained  to  the  end.  Therefore  it  seems  that  use  precedes 
command. 


COMMANDED  ACTS  197 

Obj.  3.  Further,  every  act  of  a  power  moved  by  the  will  is 
called  use;  because  the  will  uses  the  other  powers,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XVL,  A.  i).  But  command  is  an  act  of  the  reason 
as  moved  by  the  will,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  Therefore 
command  is  a  kind  of  use.  Now  the  common  precedes  the 
proper.     Therefore  use  precedes  command. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  {De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that 
impulse  to  action  precedes  use.  But  impulse  to  operation 
is  given  by  command.     Therefore  command  precedes  use. 

I  answer  that,  use  of  that  which  is  directed  to  the  end,  in 
so  far  as  it  is  in  the  reason  referring  this  to  the  end,  precedes 
choice,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XVL,  A.  4).  Wherefore  still 
more  does  it  precede  command. — On  the  other  hand,  use  of 
that  which  is  directed  to  the  end,  in  so  far  as  it  is  subject  to 
the  executive  power,  follows  command:  because  use  in  the 
user  is  united  to  the  act  of  the  thing  used ;  for  one  does  not 
use  a  stick  before  doing  something  with  the  stick.  But 
command  is  not  simultaneous  with  the  act  of  the  thing  to 
which  the  command  is  given:  for  it  naturally  precedes  its 
fulfilment,  sometimes,  indeed,  by  priority  of  time.  Conse- 
quently it  is  evident  that  command  precedes  use. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Not  every  act  of  the  will  precedes  this  act 
of  the  reason  which  is  command ;  but  an  act  of  the  will  pre- 
cedes, viz.,  choice;  and  an  act  of  the  will  follows,  viz.,  use. 
Because  after  counsel's  decision,  which  is  reason's  judgment, 
the  will  chooses;  and  after  choice,  the  reason  commands 
that  power  which  has  to  do  what  was  chosen;  and  then,  last 
of  all,  someone's  will  begins  to  use,  by  executing  the  com- 
mand of  reason;  sometimes  it  is  another's  will,  when  one 
commands  another;  sometimes  the  will  of  the  one  that 
commands,  when  he  commands  himself  to  do  something. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Just  as  act  ranks  before  power,  so  does  the 
object  rank  before  the  act.  Now  the  object  of  use  is  that 
which  is  directed  to  the  end.  Consequently,  from  the  fact 
that  command  is  directed  to  the  end,  one  should  conclude 
that  command  precedes,  rather  than  that  it  follows  use. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Just  as  the  act  of  the  will  in  using  the  reason 
for  the  purpose  of  command,  precedes  the  command ;  so  also 


198  QUESTION  XVII 

we  may  say  that  this  act  whereby  the  will  uses  the  reason, 
is  preceded  by  a  command  of  reason;  since  the  acts  of  these 
powers  react  on  one  another. 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  command  and  the  commanded  act  are 
one  act,  or  distinct  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  commanded  act  is  not  one 
with  the  command  itself.  For  the  acts  of  different  powers 
are  themselves  distinct.  But  the  commanded  act  belongs 
to  one  power,  and  the  command  to  another;  since  one  is  the 
power  that  commands,  and  the  other  is  the  power  that 
receives  the  command.  Therefore  the  commanded  act  is 
not  one  with  the  command. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  whatever  things  can  be  separate  from 
one  another,  are  distinct:  for  nothing  is  severed  from  itself. 
But  sometimes  the  commanded  act  is  separate  from  the 
command:  for  sometimes  the  command  is  given,  and  the 
commanded  act  follows  not.  Therefore  command  is  a 
distinct  act  from  the  act  commanded. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  whatever  things  are  related  to  one  another 
as  precedent  and  consequent,  are  distinct.  But  command 
naturally  precedes  the  commanded  act.  Therefore  they 
are  distinct. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Topic,  iii.)  that 
where  one  thing  is  by  reason  of  another,  there  is  but  one.  But 
there  is  no  commanded  act  unless  by  reason  of  the  command. 
Therefore  they  are  one. 

/  answer  that.  Nothing  prevents  certain  things  being 
distinct  in  one  respect,  and  one  in  another  respect.  Indeed, 
every  multitude  is  one  in  some  respect,  as  Dionysius  says 
(Div.  Nom.  xiii.).  But  a  difference  is  to  be  observed  in  this, 
that  some  are  simply  many,  and  one  in  a  particular  respect: 
while  with  others  it  is  the  reverse.  Now  one  is  predicated 
in  the  same  way  as  being.  And  substance  is  being  simply, 
whereas  accident  or  being  of  reason  is  a  being  only  in  a 


COMMANDED  ACTS  199 

certain  respect.  Wherefore  those  things  that  are  one  in 
substance  are  one  simply,  though  many  in  a  certain  respect. 
Thus,  in  the  genus  substance,  the  whole  composed  of  its 
integral  or  essential  parts,  is  one  simply:  because  the  whole 
is  being  and  substance  simply,  and  the  parts  are  beings  and 
substances  in  the  whole.  But  those  things  which  are  dis- 
tinct in  substance,  and  one  according  to  an  accident,  are 
distinct  simply,  and  one  in  a  certain  respect:  thus  many 
men  are  one  people,  and  many  stones  are  one  heap;  which 
is  unity  of  composition  or  order.  In  like  manner  also  many 
individuals  that  are  one  in  genus  or  species  are  many 
simply,  and  one  in  a  certain  respect:  since  to  be  one  in  genus 
or  species  is  to  be  one  according  to  the  consideration  of  the 
reason. 

Now  just  as  in  the  genus  of  natural  things,  a  whole  is 
composed  of  matter  and  form  (e.g.,  man,  who  is  one  natural 
being,  though  he  has  many  parts,  is  composed  of  soul  and 
body) ;  so,  in  human  acts,  the  act  of  a  lower  power  is  in  the 
position  of  matter  in  regard  to  the  act  of  a  higher  power,  in 
so  far  as  the  lower  power  acts  in  virtue  of  the  higher  power 
moving  it:  for  thus  also  the  act  of  the  first  mover  is  as  the 
form  in  regard  to  the  act  of  its  instrument.  Hence  it  is 
evident  that  command  and  the  commanded  act  are  one 
human  act,  just  as  a  whole  is  one,  yet,  in  its  parts,  many. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  If  the  distinct  powers  are  not  ordained  to 
one  another,  their  acts  are  diverse  simply.  But  when  one 
power  is  the  mover  of  the  other,  then  their  acts  are,  in  a  wa^^ 
one :  since  the  act  of  the  mover  and  the  act  of  the  thing  moved  are 
one  act  (Phys.  iii.). 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  fact  that  command  and  the  commanded 
act  can  be  separated  from  one  another  shows  that  they  are 
different  parts.  Because  the  parts  of  a  man  can  be  separ- 
ated from  one  another,  and  yet  they  form  one  whole. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  those  things  that  are  many  in  parts,  but 
one  as  a  whole,  nothing  hinders  one  part  from  preceding 
another.  Thus  the  soul,  in  a  way,  precedes  the  body;  and 
the  heart,  the  other  members. 


200  QUESTION  XVII 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  the  act  of  the  will  is  commanded  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  act  of  the  will  is  not  com- 
manded. For  Augustine  says  {Conf.  viii.):  The  mind  com- 
mands the  mind  to  will,  and  yet  it  does  not.  But  to  will  is 
the  act  of  the  will.  Therefore  the  act  of  the  will  is  not 
commanded. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  to  receive  a  command  belongs  to  one  who 
can  understand  the  command.  But  the  will  cannot  under- 
stand the  command:  for  the  will  differs  from  the  intellect, 
to  which  it  belongs  to  understand.  Therefore  the  act  of  the 
will  is  not  commanded. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  one  act  of  the  will  is  commanded,  for 
the  same  reason  all  are  commanded.  But  if  all  the  acts  of  the 
will  are  commanded,  we  must  needs  proceed  to  infinity; 
because  the  act  of  the  will  precedes  the  act  of  reason  com- 
manding, as  stated  above  (A.  i) ;  for  if  that  act  of  the  will  be 
also  commanded,  this  command  will  be  preceded  by  another 
act  of  the  reason,  and  so  on  to  infinity.  But  to  proceed  to 
infinity  is  not  possible.  Therefore  the  act  of  the  will  is  not 
commanded. 

On  the  contrary,  Whatever  is  in  our  power,  is  subject  to  our 
command.  But  the  acts  of  the  will,  most  of  all,  are  in  our 
power;  since  all  our  acts  are  said  to  be  in  our  power,  in  so  far 
as  they  are  voluntary.  Therefore  the  acts  of  the  will  are 
commanded  by  us. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  command  is  nothing 
else  than  the  act  of  the  reason  directing,  with  a  certain 
motion,  something  to  act.  Now  it  is  evident  that  the 
reason  can  direct  the  act  of  the  will :  for  just  as  it  can  judge 
it  to  be  good  to  will  something,  so  it  can  direct  by  com- 
manding man  to  will.  From  this  it  is  evident  that  an  act  of 
the  will  can  be  commanded. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  Augustine  says  {ihid.)  when  the  mind 
commands  itself  perfectly  to  will,  then  already  it  wills:  but 


COMMANDED  ACTS  201 

that  sometimes  it  commands  and  wills  not,  is  due  to  the 
fact  that  it  commands  imperfectly.  Now  imperfect  com- 
mand arises  from  the  fact  that  the  reason  is  moved  by  oppo- 
site motives  to  command  or  not  to  command:  wherefore  il 
fluctuates  between  the  two,  and  fails  to  command  perfectly. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Just  as  each  of  the  members  of  the  body 
works  not  for  itself  alone  but  for  the  whole  body;  thus  it  is 
for  the  whole  body  that  the  eye  sees;  so  is  it  with  the  powers 
of  the  soul.  For  the  intellect  understands,  not  for  itself 
alone,  but  for  all  the  powers;  and  the  will  wills  not  only  for 
itself,  but  for  all  the  powers  too.  Wherefore  man,  in  so  far 
as  he  is  endowed  with  intellect  and  will,  commands  the  act 
of  the  will  for  himself. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Since  command  is  an  act  of  the  reason,  that 
act  is  commanded  which  is  subject  to  reason.  Now  the 
first  act  of  the  will  is  not  due  to  the  direction  of  the  reason 
but  to  the  instigation  of  nature,  or  of  a  higher  cause,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  4).  Therefore  there  is  no  need  to  proceed 
to  infinity. 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  the  act  of  the  reason  is  commanded  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  act  of  the  reason  cannot  be 
commanded .  For  it  seems  impossible  for  a  thing  to  command 
itself.  But  it  is  the  reason  that  commands,  as  stated  above 
(A.  i).     Therefore  the  act  of  the  reason  is  not  commanded. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  that  which  is  essential  is  different  from 
that  which  is  by  participation.  But  the  power  whose  act  is 
commanded  by  reason,  is  rational  by  participation,  as  stated 
in  Ethic,  i.  Therefore  the  act  of  that  power,  which  is 
essentially  rational,  is  not  commanded. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  that  act  is  commanded,  which  is  in  our 
power.  But  to  know  and  judge  the  truth,  which  is  the  act 
of  reason,  is  not  always  in  our  power.  Therefore  the  act  of 
the  reason  cannot  be  commanded. 

On  the  contrary,  That  which  we  do  of  our  free-will,  can  be 
done  by  our  command.     But  the  acts  of  the  reason  are 


202  QUESTION  XVII 

accomplished  through  the  free-will:  for  Damascene  says 
(De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that  by  his  free-will  man  inquires,  con- 
siders, judges,  approves.  Therefore  the  acts  of  the  reason 
can  be  commanded. 

I  answer  that.  Since  the  reason  re-acts  on  itself,  just  as  it 
directs  the  acts  of  other  powers,  so  can  it  direct  its  own  act. 
Consequently  its  act  can  be  commanded. 

But  we  must  take  note  that  the  act  of  the  reason  may  be 
considered  in  two  ways.  First,  as  to  the  exercise  of  the  act. 
And  considered  thus,  the  act  of  the  reason  can  always  be 
commanded:  as  when  one  is  told  to  be  attentive,  and  to  use 
one's  reason.  Secondly,  as  to  the  object;  in  respect  of 
which  two  acts  of  the  reason  have  to  be  noticed.  One  is  the 
act  whereby  it  apprehends  the  truth  about  something. 
This  act  is  not  in  our  power :  because  it  happens  in  virtue  of 
a  natural  or  supernatural  light.  Consequently  in  this 
respect,  the  act  of  the  reason  is  not  in  our  power,  and  cannot 
be  commanded.  The  other  act  of  the  reason  is  that  whereby 
it  assents  to  what  it  apprehends.  If,  therefore,  that  which 
the  reason  apprehends  is  such  that  it  naturally  assents 
thereto,  e.g.,  the  first  principles,  it  is  not  in  our  power  to 
assent  or  dissent  to  the  like:  assent  follows  naturally,  and 
consequently,  properly  speaking,  is  not  subject  to  our  com- 
mand. But  some  things  are  apprehended  which  do  not 
convince  the  intellect  so  that  one  cannot  assent  or  dissent, 
or  at  least  suspend  one's  assent  or  dissent,  on  account  of 
some  cause  or  other:  and  in  such  things  assent  or  dissent  is 
in  our  power,  and  is  subject  to  our  command. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Reason  commands  itself,  just  as  the  will 
moves  itself,  as  stated  above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  3),  that  is  to  say, 
in  so  far  as  each  power  reacts  on  its  own  act,  and  from  one 
thing  tends  to  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  On  account  of  the  diversity  of  objects 
subject  to  the  act  of  the  reason,  nothing  prevents  the  reason 
from  participating  in  itself:  thus  the  knowledge  of  prin- 
ciples is  participated  in  the  knowledge  of  the  conclusions. 

The  reply  to  the  third  objection  is  evident  from  what  has 
been  said. 


COMMANDED  ACTS  203 


Seventh  Article. 

whether  the  act  of  the  sensitive  appetite 
is  commanded  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  act  of  the  sensitive  appetite 
is  not  commanded.  For  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  vii.  15): 
For  I  do  not  that  good  which  I  will :  and  a  gloss  explains  this 
by  saying  that  man  lusts,  although  he  wills  not  to  lust. 
But  to  lust  is  an  act  of  the  sensitive  appetite.  Therefore 
the  act  of  the  sensitive  appetite  is  not  subject  to  our  com- 
mand. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  corporeal  matter  obeys  God  alone,  to  the 
effect  of  formal  transmutation,  as  was  shown  in  the  First 
Part  (Q.  LXV.,  A.  4;  Q.  XCI.,  A.  2;  Q.  CX.,  A.  2).  But  the 
act  of  the  sensitive  appetite  is  accompanied  by  a  formal 
transmutation  of  the  body,  consisting  in  heat  or  cold.  There- 
fore the  act  of  the  sensitive  appetite  is  not  subject  to  man's 
command. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  proper  motive  principle  of  the  sensi- 
tive appetite  is  something  apprehended  by  sense  or  imagina- 
tion. But  it  is  not  always  in  our  power  to  apprehend  some- 
thing by  sense  or  imagination.  Therefore  the  act  of  the 
sensitive  appetite  is  not  subject  to  our  command. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat. 
Horn,  xvi.)  says:  That  which  obeys  reason  is  twofold,  the  con- 
cupiscible  and  the  irascible,  which  belong  to  the  sensitive 
appetite.  Therefore  the  act  of  the  sensitive  appetite  is 
subject  to  the  command  of  reason. 

I  answer  that,  An  act  is  subject  to  our  command,  in  so  far 
as  it  is  in  our  power,  as  stated  above  (A.  5).  Consequently 
in  order  to  understand  in  what  manner  the  act  of  the  sensi- 
tive appetite  is  subject  to  the  command  of  reason,  we  must 
consider  in  what  manner  it  is  in  our  power.  Now  it  must 
be  observed  that  the  sensitive  appetite  differs  from  the 
intellective  appetite,  which  is  called  the  will,  in  the  fact 
that  the  sensitive  appetite  is  the  power  of  a  corporeal  organ. 


204  QUESTION  XVII 

whereas  the  will  is  not.  Again,  every  act  of  a  power  that 
uses  a  corporeal  organ,  depends  not  only  on  a  power  of  the 
soul,  but  also  on  the  disposition  of  that  corporeal  organ: 
thus  the  act  of  vision  depends  on  the  power  of  sight,  and  on 
the  condition  of  the  eye,  which  condition  is  a  help  or  a 
hindrance  to  that  act.  Consequently  the  act  of  the  sensitive 
appetite  depends  not  only  on  the  appetitive  power,  but  also 
on  the  disposition  of  the  body. 

Now  whatever  part  the  power  of  the  soul  takes  in  the  act, 
follows  apprehension.  And  the  apprehension  of  the  im- 
agination, being  a  particular  apprehension,  is  regulated  by 
the  apprehension  of  reason,  which  is  universal;  just  as  a 
particular  active  power  is  regulated  by  a  universal  active 
power.  Consequently  in  this  respect  the  act  of  the  sensitive 
appetite  is  subject  to  the  command  of  reason. — On  the  other 
hand,  condition  or  disposition  of  the  body  is  not  subject  to 
the  command  of  reas5n:  and  consequently  in  this  respect, 
the  movement  of  the  sensitive  appetite  is  hindered  from  being 
wholly  subject  to  the  command  of  reason. 

Moreover  it  happens  sometimes  that  the  movement  of  the 
sensitive  appetite  is  aroused  suddenly  in  consequence  of  an 
apprehension  of  the  imagination  or  sense.  And  then  such 
movement  occurs  without  the  command  of  reason:  although 
reason  could  have  prevented  it,  had  it  foreseen.  Hence  the 
Philosopher  says  {Polit.  i.)  that  the  reason  governs  the 
irascible  and  concupiscible  not  by  a  despotic  supremacy^ 
which  is  that  of  a  master  over  his  slave;  but  by  a  politic  and 
royal  supremacy,  whereby  the  free  are  governed,  who  are  not 
wholly  subject  to  command. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  That  man  lusts,  although  he  wills  not  to  lust, 
is  due  to  a  disposition  of  the  body,  whereby  the  sensitive 
appetite  is  hindered  from  perfect  compliance  to  the  com- 
mand of  reason.  Hence  the  Apostle  adds  {ibid.):  I  see 
another  law  in  my  members,  fighting  against  the  law  of  my 
mind. — This  may  also  happen  through  a  sudden  movement 
of  concupiscence,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  condition  of  the  body  stands  in  a  two- 
fold relation  to  the  act  of  the  sensitive  appetite.     First,  as 


COMMANDED  ACTS  205 

preceding  it:  thus  a  man  may  be  disposed  in  one  way  or 
another,  in  respect  of  his  body,  to  this  or  that  passion. 
Secondly,  as  consequent  to  it:  thus  a  man  becomes  heated 
through  anger.  Now  the  condition  that  precedes,  is  not 
subject  to  the  command  of  reason:  since  it  is  due  either  to 
nature,  or  to  some  previous  movement,  which  cannot  cease 
at  once.  But  the  condition  that  is  consequent,  follows  the 
command  of  reason:  since  it  results  from  the  local  move- 
ment of  the  heart,  which  has  various  movements  according 
to  the  various  acts  of  the  sensitive  appetite. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Since  the  external  sensible  is  necessary  for 
the  apprehension  of  the  senses,  it  is  not  in  our  power  to 
apprehend  anything  by  the  senses,  unless  the  sensible  be 
present;  which  presence  of  the  sensible  is  not  always  in  our 
power.  For  it  is  then  that  man  can  use  his  senses  if  he  will 
so  to  do;  unless  there  be  some  obstacle  on  the  part  of  the 
organ. — On  the  other  hand,  the  apprehension  of  the  imagina- 
tion is  subject  to  the  ordering  of  reason,  in  proportion  to  the 
strength  or  weakness  of  the  imaginative  power.  For  that 
man  is  unable  to  imagine  the  things  that  reason  considers, 
is  either  because  they  cannot  be  imagined,  such  as  in- 
corporeal things ;  or  because  of  the  weakness  of  the  imagina- 
tive power,  due  to  some  organic  indisposition. 

Eighth  Article. 

whether  the  act  of  the  vegetal  soul  is 
commanded  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  acts  of  the  vegetal  soul  are 
subject  to  the  command  of  reason.  For  the  sensitive 
powers  are  of  higher  rank  than  the  vegetal  powers.  But  the 
powers  of  the  sensitive  soul  are  subject  to  the  command 
of  reason.  Much  more,  therefore,  are  the  powers  of  the 
vegetal  soul. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  man  is  called  a  little  world,  because  the 
soul  is  in  the  body,  as  God  is  in  the  world.  But  God  is  in 
the  world  in  such  a  way,  that  everything  in  the  world  obeys 


2o6  QUESTION  XVII 

His  command.     Therefore   all   that  is   in  man,    even  the 
powers  of  the  vegetal  soul,  obey  the  command  of  reason. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  praise  and  blame  are  awarded  only  to 
such  acts  as  are  subject  to  the  command  of  reason.  But 
in  the  acts  of  the  nutritive  and  generative  power,  there  is 
room  for  praise  and  blame,  virtue  and  vice :  as  in  the  case  of 
gluttony  and  lust,  and  their  contrary  virtues.  Therefore 
the  acts  of  these  powers  are  subject  to  the  command  of 
reason. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat. 
Horn,  xvi.)  says  that  the  nutritive  and  generative  power  is  one 
over  which  the  reason  has  no  control. 

I  answer  that,  Some  acts  proceed  from  the  natural  appetite, 
others  from  the  animal,  or  from  the  intellectual  appetite: 
for  every  agent  desires  an  end  in  some  way.  Now  the 
natural  appetite  does  not  follow  from  some  apprehension,  as 
do  the  animal  and  the  intellectual  appetite.  But  the 
reason  commands  by  way  of  an  apprehensive  power.  Where- 
fore those  acts  that  proceed  from  the  intellective  or  the 
animal  appetite,  can  be  commanded  by  the  reason:  but  not 
those  acts  that  proceed  from  the  natural  appetite.  And 
such  are  the  acts  of  the  vegetal  soul ;  wherefore  Gregory  of 
Nyssa  (Nemesius, — loc.  cit.)  says  that  generation  and  nutri- 
tion belong  to  what  are  called  natural  powers.  Consequently 
the  acts  of  the  vegetal  soul  are  not  subject  to  the  command 
of  reason. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  more  immaterial  an  act  is,  the  more 
noble  it  is,  and  the  more  is  it  subject  to  the  command  of 
reason.  Hence  the  very  fact  that  the  acts  of  the  vegetal 
soul  do  not  obey  reason,  shows  that  they  rank  lowest. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  comparison  holds  in  a  certain  respect: 
because,  to  wit,  as  God  moves  the  world,  so  the  soul  moves 
the  body.  But  it  does  not  hold  in  every  respect:  for  the 
soul  did  not  create  the  body  out  of  nothing,  as  God  created 
the  world;  for  which  reason  the  world  is  wholly  subject  to 
His  command. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Virtue  and  vice,  praise  and  blame  do  not 
affect  the  acts  themselves  of  the  nutritive  and  generative 


COMMANDED  ACTS  207 

power,  i.e.,  digestion,  and  formation  of  the  human  body; 
but  they  affect  the  acts  of  the  sensitive  part,  that  are 
ordained  to  the  acts  of  generation  and  nutrition;  for  example 
the  desire  for  pleasure  in  the  act  of  taking  food  or  in  the 
act  of  generation,  and  the  right  or  wrong  use  thereof. 


Ninth  Article. 

whether  the  acts  of  the  external  members 
are  commanded  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Ninth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  members  of  the  body  do  not 
obey  reason  as  to  their  acts.  For  it  is  evident  that  the 
members  of  the  body  are  more  distant  from  the  reason,  than 
the  powers  of  the  vegetal  soul.  But  the  powers  of  the 
vegetal  soul  do  not  obey  reason,  as  stated  above  (A.  8). 
Therefore  much  less  do  the  members  of  the  body  obey. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  heart  is  the  principle  of  animal 
movement.  But  the  movement  of  the  heart  is  not  subject 
to  the  command  of  reason:  for  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, 
— De  Nat.  Horn,  xxii.)  says  that  the  pulse  is  not  controlled  by 
reason.  Therefore  the  movement  of  the  bodily  members  is 
not  subject  to  the  command  of  reason. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  that 
the  movement  of  the  genital  members  is  sometimes  inopportune 
and  not  desired ;  sometimes  when  sought  it  fails,  and  whereas 
the  heart  is  warm  with  desire,  the  body  remains  cold.  There- 
fore the  movements  of  the  members  are  not  obedient  to 
reason. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Conf.  viii.) :  The  mind 
commands  a  movement  of  the  hand,  and  so  ready  is  the  hand  to 
obey,  that  scarcely  can  one  discern  obedience  from  command. 

I  answer  that,  The  members  of  the  body  are  organs  of  the 
soul's  powers.  Consequently  according  as  the  powers  of  the 
soul  stand  in  respect  of  obedience  to  reason,  so  do  the 
members  of  the  body  stand  in  respect  thereof.  Since  then 
the  sensitive  powers  are  subject  to  the  command  of  reason, 
whereas  the  natural  powers  are  not;  therefore  all  move- 


208  QUESTION  XVII 

ments  of  members,  that  are  moved  by  the  sensitive  powers, 
are  subject  to  the  command  of  reason;  whereas  those  move- 
ments of  members,  that  arise  from  the  natural  powers,  are 
not  subject  to  the  command  of  reason. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  members  do  not  move  themselves,  but 
are  moved  through  the  powers  of  the  soul ;  of  which  powers, 
some  are  in  closer  contact  with  the  reason  than  are  the 
powers  of  the  vegetal  soul. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  In  things  pertaining  to  intellect  and  will, 
that  which  is  according  to  nature  stands  first,  whence  all 
other  things  are  derived:  thus  from  the  knowledge  of 
principles  that  are  naturally  known,  we  desire  knowledge 
of  the  conclusions;  and  from  volition  of  the  end  naturally 
desired,  we  desire  the  choice  of  the  means.  So  also  in 
bodily  movements  the  principle  is  according  to  nature. 
Now  the  principle  of  bodily  movements  begins  with  the 
movement  of  the  heart.  Consequently  the  movement  of 
the  heart  is  according  to  nature,  and  not  according  to  the 
will:  for  like  a  proper  accident,  it  results  from  life,  which 
follows  from  the  union  of  soul  and  body.  Thus  the  move- 
ment of  heavy  and  light  things  results  from  their  substantial 
form:  for  which  reason  they  are  said  to  be  moved  by  their 
generator,  as  the  Philosopher  states  (Phys.  viii) .  Wherefore 
this  movement  is  called  vitaL  For  which  reason  Gregory  of 
Nyssa  (Nemesius, — loc.  cit)  says  that,  just  as  the  movement 
of  generation  and  nutrition  does  not  obey  reason,  so  neither 
does  the  pulse  which  is  a  vital  movement.  By  the  palse  he 
means  the  movement  of  the  heart  which  is  indicated  by  the 
pulse  veins. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  it  is 
in  punishment  of  sin  that  the  movement  of  these  mem- 
bers does  not  obey  reason:  in  this  sense,  that  the  soul  is 
punished  for  its  rebellion  against  God,  by  the  insubmission 
of  that  member  whereby  original  sin  is  transmitted  to  pos- 
terity. 

But  because,  as  we  shall  state  later  on,  the  effect  of  the 
sin  of  our  first  parent  was  that  his  nature  was  left  to  itself, 
through  the  withdrawal  of  the  supernatural  gift  which  God 


COMMANDED  ACTS  209 

had  bestowed  on  man;  we  must  consider  the  natural  cause 
of  this  particular  member's  insubmission  to  reason.  This  is 
stated  by  Aristotle  (De  Causis  Mot.  Animal.)  who  says  that 
the  movements  of  the  heart  and  of  the  organs  of  generation  are 
involuntary,  and  that  the  reason  of  this  is  as  follows.  These 
members  are  stirred  at  the  occasion  of  some  apprehension; 
in  so  far  as  the  intellect  and  imagination  represent  such 
things  as  arouse  the  passions  of  the  soul,  of  which  passions 
these  movements  are  a  consequence.  But  they  are  not 
moved  at  the  command  of  the  reason  or  intellect,  because 
these  movements  are  conditioned  by  a  certain  natural  change 
of  heat  and  cold,  which  change  is  not  subject  to  the  command 
of  reason.  This  is  the  case  with  these  two  organs  in  par- 
ticular, because  each  is  as  it  were  a  separate  animal  being, 
in  so  far  as  it  is  a  principle  of  life;  and  the  principle  is  virtu- 
ally the  whole.  For  the  heart  is  the  principle  of  the  senses ; 
and  from  the  organ  of  generation  proceeds  the  seminal 
virtue,  which  is  virtually  the  entire  animal.  Consequently 
they  have  their  proper  movements  naturally:  because 
principles  must  needs  be  natural,  as  stated  above.  (Reply 
Obi.  2). 


II   I 


14 


QUESTION  XVIII. 

OF  THE  GOOD  AND  EVIL  OF  HUMAN  ACTS,  IN  GENERAL. 

{In  Eleven  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  good  and  evil  of  human  acts. 
First,  how  a  human  act  is  good  or  evil;  secondly,  what 
results  from  the  good  or  evil  of  a  human  act,  as  merit  or 
demerit,  sin  and  guilt. 

Under  the  first  head  there  will  be  a  threefold  consider- 
ation: the  first  will  be  of  the  good  and  evil  of  human  acts, 
in  general;  the  second,  of  the  good  and  evil  of  internal  acts; 
the  third,  of  the  good  and  evil  of  external  acts. 

Concerning  the  first  there  are  eleven  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  every  human  action  is  good,  or  are  there  evil 
actions  ?  (2)  Whether  the  good  or  evil  of  a  human  action 
is  derived  from  its  object  ?  (3)  Whether  it  is  derived  from 
a  circumstance  ?     (4)  Whether  it  is  derived  from  the  end  ? 

(5)  Whether  a  human  action  is  good  or  evil  in  its  species  ? 

(6)  Whether  an  action  has  the  species  of  good  or  evil  from 
its  end  ?  (7)  Whether  the  species  derived  from  the  end  is 
contained  under  the  species  derived  from  the  object,  as 
under  its  genus,  or  conversely  ?  (8)  Whether  any  action 
is  indifferent  in  its  species  ?  (9)  Whether  an  individual 
action  can  be  indifferent  ?  (10)  Whether  a  circumstance 
places  a  moral  action  in  the  species  of  good  or  evil  ?  (11) 
Whether  every  circumstance  that  makes  an  action  better 
or  worse,  places  the  moral  action  in  the  species  of  good  or 
evil  ? 


210 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  21  r 


First  Article. 

whether  every  human  action  is  good,  or  are 
there  evil  actions  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  every  human  action  is  good, 
and  that  none  is  evil.  For  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Noni.  iv.) 
that  evil  acts  not,  save  in  virtue  of  the  good.  But  no  evil  is 
done  in  virtue  of  the  good.     Therefore  no  action  is  evil. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  nothing  acts  except  in  so  far  as  it  is  in 
act.  Now  a  thing  is  evil,  not  according  as  it  is  in  act,  but 
according  as  its  potentiality  is  void  of  act ;  whereas  in  so  far 
as  its  potentiality  is  perfected  by  act,  it  is  good,  as  stated  in 
Metaph.  ix.  Therefore  nothing  acts  in  so  far  as  it  is  evil, 
but  only  according  as  it  is  good.  Therefore  every  action  is 
good,  and  none  is  evil. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  evil  cannot  be  a  cause,  save  accidentally, 
'as  Dionysius  declares  (Div.  Nom.  iv.).  But  every  action 
has  some  effect  which  is  proper  to  it.  Therefore  no  action 
is  evil,  but  every  action  is  good. 

On  the  contrary,  Our  Lord  said  (John  iii.  20):  Every  one 
that  doth  evil,  hateth  the  light.  Therefore  some  actions  of  man 
are  evil. 

I  answer  that,  We  must  speak  of  good  and  evil  in  actions, 
as  of  good  and  evil  in  things :  because  such  as  everything  is 
such  is  the  act  that  it  produces.  Now  in  things,  each  one 
has  so  much  good  as  it  has  being :  since  good  and  being  are 
convertible,  as  was  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  V.  AA.  i,  3). 
But  God  alone  has  the  whole  plenitude  of  His  Being  in  a 
certain  unity:  whereas  every  other  thing  has  its  proper 
fulness  of  being  in  a  certain  multiplicity.  Wherefore  it 
happens  with  some  things,  that  they  have  being  in  some 
respect,  and  yet  they  are  lacking  in  the  fulness  of  being  due 
to  them.  Thus  the  fulness  of  human  being  requires  a 
compound  of  soul  and  body,  having  all  the  powers  and 
instruments  of  knowledge  and  movement:  wherefore  if  any 
man  be  lacking  in  any  of  these,  he  is  lacking  in  something  due 


212  QUESTION  XVIII 

to  the  fulness  of  his  being.  So  that  as  much  as  he  has  of 
being,  so  much  has  he  of  goodness:  while  so  far  as  he  is 
lacking  in  the  fulness  of  his  being,  so  far  is  he  lacking  in 
goodness,  and  is  said  to  be  evil :  thus  a  blind  man  is  pos- 
sessed of  goodness  in  as  much  as  he  lives;  and  of  evil,  inas- 
much as  he  lacks  sight.  That,  however,  which  has  nothing 
of  being  or  goodness,  could  not  be  said  to  be  either  evil  or 
good.  But  since  this  same  fulness  of  being  is  of  the  very 
essence  of  good,  if  a  thing  be  lacking  in  its  due  fulness  of 
being,  it  is  not  said  to  be  good  simply,  but  in  a  certain 
respect,  inasmuch  as  it  is  a  being ;  although  it  can  be  called 
a  being  simply,  and  a  non-being  in  a  certain  respect,  as  was 
stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  V.,  A.  i  ad.  i).  We  must  there- 
fore say  that  every  action  has  goodness,  in  so  far  as  it  has 
being:  whereas  it  is  lacking  in  goodness,  in  so  far  as  it  is 
lacking  in  something  that  is  due  to  its  fulness  of  being;  and 
thus  it  is  said  to  be  evil:  for  instance  if  it  lacks  the  quantity 
determined  by  reason,  or  its  due  place,  or  something  of  the 
kind. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Evil  acts  in  virtue  of  deficient  goodness. 
For  if  there  were  nothing  of  good  there,  there  would  be 
neither  being  nor  possibility  of  action.  On  the  other  hand 
if  good  were  not  deficient,  there  would  be  no  evil.  Con- 
sequently the  action  done  is  a  deficient  good,  which  is  good 
in  a  certain  respect,  but  simply  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Nothing  hinders  a  thing  from  being  in  act 
in  a  certain  respect,  so  that  it  can  act;  and  in  a  certain 
respect  deficient  in  act,  so  as  to  cause  a  deficient  act.  Thus 
a  blind  man  has  in  act  the  power  of  walking,  whereby  he  is 
able  to  walk;  but  inasmuch  as  he  is  deprived  of  sight  he 
suffers  a  defect  in  walking  by  stumbling  when  he  walks. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  An  evil  action  can  have  a  proper  effect, 
according  to  the  goodness  and  being  that  it  has.  Thus 
adultery  is  the  cause  of  human  generation,  inasmuch  as  it 
implies  union  of  male  and  female,  but  not  inasmuch  as  it 
lacks  the  order  of  reason. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  213 

Second  Article. 

WHETHER   THE   GOOD   OR  EVIL  OF   A  MAN'S   ACTION 
IS   DERIVED    FROM   ITS   OBJECT  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  good  or  evil  of  an  action  is 
not  derived  from  its  object.  For  the  object  of  an  action  is  a 
thing.  But  evil  is  not  in  things,  but  in  the  sinner's  use  of  them, 
as  Augustine  says  {De  Doctr.  Christ,  iii.).  Therefore  the  good 
or  evil  of  a  human  action  is  not  derived  from  its  object. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  object  is  compared  to  the  action  as 
its  matter.  But  the  goodness  of  a  thing  is  not  from  its 
matter,  but  rather  from  the  form,  which  is  an  act.  There- 
fore good  and  evil  in  actions  is  not  derived  from  their  object. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  object  of  an  active  power  is  com- 
pared to  the  action  as  effect  to  cause.  But  the  goodness  of 
a  cause  does  not  depend  on  its  effect;  rather  is  it  the  re- 
verse. Therefore  good  or  evil  in  actions  is  not  derived  from 
their  object. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  (Osee  ix.  10) :  They  became 
abominable  as  those  things  which  they  loved.  Now  man  be- 
comes abominable  to  God  on  account  of  the  malice  of  his 
action.  Therefore  the  malice  of  his  action  is  according  to 
the  evil  objects  that  man  loves.  And  the  same  applies  to 
the  goodness  of  his  action. 

/  answer  that,  as  stated  above  (A.  i)  the  good  or  evil  of  an 
action,  as  of  other  things,  depends  on  its  fulness  of  being 
or  its  lack  of  that  fulness.  Now  the  first  thing  that  belongs 
to  the  fulness  of  being  seems  to  be  that  which  gives  a  thing 
its  species.  And  just  as  a  natural  thing  has  its  species  from 
its  form,  so  an  action  has  its  species  from  its  object,  as  move- 
ment from  its  term.  And  therefore,  just  as  the  primary 
goodness  of  a  natural  thing  is  derived  from  its  form,  which 
gives  it  its  species,  so  the  primary  goodness  of  a  moral  action 
is  derived  from  its  suitable  object:  hence  some  call  such  an 
action  good  in  its  genus  ;  for  instance,  to  make  use  of  what 
is  one's  own.     And  just  as,  in  natural  things,  the  primary 


214  QUESTION  XVIII 

evil  is  when  a  generated  thing  does  not  reaHze  its  specific 
form  (for  instance,  if  instead  of  a  man,  something  else  be 
generated) ;  so  the  primary  evil  in  moral  actions  is  that  which 
is  from  the  object,  for  instance,  to  take  what  belongs  to  an- 
other. And  this  action  is  said  to  be  evil  in  its  genus,  genus 
here  standing  for  species,  just  as  we  apply  the  term  mankind 
to  the  whole  human  species. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Although  external  things  are  good  in  them- 
selves, nevertheless  they  have  not  always  a  due  proportion 
to  this  or  that  action.  And  so,  inasmuch  as  they  are  con- 
sidered as  objects  of  such  actions,  they  have  not  the  qualit}^ 
of  goodness. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  object  is  not  the  matter  of  which  (a 
thing  is  made),  but  the  matter  about  which  (something  is 
done) ;  and  stands  in  relation  to  the  act  as  its  form,  as  it 
were,  through  giving  it  its  species. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  object  of  the  human  action  is  not  always 
the  object  of  an  active  power.  For  the  appetitive  power  is, 
in  a  way,  passive;  in  so  far  as  it  is  moved  by  the  appetible 
object;  and  yet  it  is  a  principle  of  human  actions. — Nor 
again  have  the  objects  of  the  active  powers  always  the  nature 
of  an  effect,  but  only  when  they  are  already  transformed: 
thus  food  when  transformed  is  the  effect  of  the  nutritive 
power;  whereas  food  before  being  transformed  stands  in 
relation  to  the  nutritive  power  as  the  matter  about  which  it 
exercises  its  operation.  Now  since  the  object  is  in  some  way 
the  effect  of  the  active  power,  it  follows  that  it  is  the  term 
of  its  action,  and  consequently  that  it  gives  it  its  form  and 
species,  since  movement  derives  its  species  from  its  terms. — 
Moreover,  although  the  goodness  of  an  action  is  not  caused 
by  the  goodness  of  its  effect,  yet  an  action  is  said  to  be  good 
from  the  fact  that  it  can  produce  a  good  effect.  Conse- 
quently the  very  proportion  of  an  action  to  its  effect  is  the 
measure  of  its  goodness. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  215 

Third  Article. 

WHETHER  man's   ACTION    IS   GOOD   OR  EVIL   FROM 
A   CIRCUMSTANCE  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  an  action  is  not  good  or  evil 
from  a  circumstance.  For  circumstances  stand  around 
(circumstant)  an  action,  as  being  outside  it,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  VII.,  A.  i).  But  good  and  evil  are  in  things  themselves,  as 
is  stated  in  Metaph.  vi.  Therefore  an  action  does  not  derive 
goodness  or  malice  from  a  circumstance. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  goodness  or  malice  of  an  action  is  con- 
sidered principally  in  the  doctrine  of  morals.  But  since 
circumstances  are  accidents  of  actions,  it  seems  that  they 
are  outside  the  scope  of  art:  because  no  art  takes  notice  oj 
what  is  accidental  {Metaph.  vi.).  Therefore  the  goodness  or 
malice  of  an  action  is  not  taken  from  a  circumstance. 

Oh].  3.  Further,  that  which  belongs  to  a  thing,  in  respect 
of  its  substance,  is  not  ascribed  to  it  in  respect  of  an  accident. 
But  good  and  evil  belong  to  an  action  in  respect  of  its  sub- 
stance; because  an  action  can  be  good  or  evil  in  its  genus 
as  stated  above  (A.  2).  Therefore  an  action  is  not  good  or 
bad  from  a  circumstance. 

On  the  contrary,  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  ii.)  that  a 
virtuous  man  acts  as  he  should,  and  when  he  should,  and  so 
on  in  respect  of  the  other  circumstances.  Therefore,  on 
the  other  hand,  the  vicious  man,  in  the  matter  of  each  vice, 
acts  when  he  should  not,  or  where  he  should  not,  and  so  on 
with  the  other  circumstances.  Therefore  human  actions 
are  good  or  evil  according  to  circumstances. 

/  answer  that.  In  natural  things,  it  is  to  be  noted  that  the 
whole  fulness  of  perfection  due  to  a  thing,  is  not  from  the 
mere  substantial  form,  that  gives  it  its  species;  since  a  thing 
derives  much  from  supervening  accidents,  as  man  does  from 
shape,  colour,  and  the  like;  and  if  any  one  of  these  accidents 
be  out  of  due  proportion,  evil  is  the  result.  So  is  it  with 
action.     For  the  plenitude  of  its  goodness  does  not  consist 


2i6  QUESTION  XVIII 

wholly  in  its  species,  but  also  in  certain  additions  which 
accrue  to  it  by  reason  of  certain  accidents:  and  such  are  its 
due  circumstances.  Wherefore  if  something  be  wanting 
that  is  requisite  as  a  due  circumstance  the  action  will  be  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Circumstances  are  outside  an  action,  inas- 
much as  they  are  not  part  of  its  essence;  but  they  are  in  an 
action  as  accidents  thereof.  Thus,  too,  accidents  in  natural 
substances  are  outside  the  essence. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Every  accident  is  not  accidentally  in  its 
subject;  for  some  are  proper  accidents;  and  of  these  every 
art  takes  notice.  And  thus  it  is  that  the  circumstances  of 
actions  are  considered  in  the  doctrine  of  morals. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Since  good  and  being  are  convertible;  ac- 
cording as  being  is  predicated  of  substance  and  of  accident, 
so  is  good  predicated  of  a  thing  both  in  respect  of  its  essential 
being,  and  in  respect  of  its  accidental  being;  and  this,  both 
in  natural  things  and  in  moral  actions. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  a  human  action  is  good  or  evil 
from  its  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  good  and  evil  in  human 
actions  are  not  from  the  end.  For  Dionysius  says  (Div. 
Nom.  iv.)  that  nothing  acts  with  a  view  to  evil.  If  therefore 
an  action  were  good  or  evil  from  its  end,  no  action  would  be 
evil.     Which  is  clearly  false. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  goodness  of  an  action  is  something  in 
the  action.  But  the  end  is  an  extrinsic  cause.  Therefore 
an  action  is  not  said  to  be  good  or  bad  according  to  its  end. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  a  good  action  may  happen  to  be  ordained 
to  an  evil  end,  as  when  a  man  gives  an  alms  from  vainglory; 
and  conversely,  an  evil  action  may  happen  to  be  ordained 
to  a  good  end,  as  a  theft  committed  in  order  to  give  some- 
thing to  the  poor.  Therefore  an  action  is  not  good  or  evil 
from  its  end. 

On  the  contrary,  Boethius  says  (De  Differ.  Topic,  n.)  that 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  217 

if  the  end  is  good,  the  thing  is  good,  and  if  the  end  he  evil,  the 
thing  also  is  evil. 

I  answer  that,  The  disposition  of  things  as  to  goodness  is 
the  same  as  their  disposition  as  to  being.  Now  in  some  things 
the  being  does  not  depend  on  another,  and  in  these  it 
suffices  to  consider  their  being  absolutely.  But  these  are 
things  the  being  of  which  depends  on  something  else,  and 
hence  in  their  regard  we  must  consider  their  being  in  its 
relation  to  the  cause  on  which  it  depends.  Now  just  as  the 
being  of  a  thing  depends  on  the  agent  and  the  form,  so  the 
goodness  of  a  thing  depends  on  its  end.  Hence  in  the 
Divine  Persons,  Whose  goodness  does  not  depend  on  another, 
the  measure  of  goodness  is  not  taken  from  the  end.  Where- 
as human  actions,  and  other  things,  the  goodness  of  which 
depends  on  something  else,  have  a  measure  of  goodness 
from  the  end  on  which  they  depend,  besides  that  goodness 
which  is  in  them  absolutely. 

Accordingly  a  fourfold  goodness  may  be  considered  in  a 
human  action.  First,  that  which,  as  an  action,  it  derives 
from  its  genus;  because  as  much  as  it  has  of  action  and 
being  so  much  has  it  of  goodness,  as  stated  above  (A.  i). 
Secondly,  it  has  goodness  according  to  its  species;  which  is 
derived  from  its  suitable  object.  Thirdly,  it  has  goodness 
from  its  circumstances,  in  respect,  as  it  were,  of  its  accidents. 
Fourthly,  it  has  goodness  from  its  end,  to  which  it  is  com- 
pared as  to  the  cause  of  its  goodness. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  good  in  view  of  which  one  acts  is  not 
always  a  true  good;  but  sometimes  it  is  a  true  good,  some- 
times an  apparent  good.  And  in  the  latter  event,  an  evil 
action  results  from  the  end  in  view. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  the  end  is  an  extrinsic  cause, 
nevertheless  due  proportion  to  the  end,  and  relation  to  the 
end,  are  inherent  to  the  action. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Nothing  hinders  an  action  that  is  good  in  one 
of  the  ways  mentioned  above,  from  lacking  goodness  in 
another  way.  And  thus  it  may  happen  that  an  action  which 
is  good  in  its  species  or  in  its  circumstances,  is  ordained  to  an 
evil  end,  or  vice  versa.     However,  an  action  is  not  good 


2i8  QUESTION  XVIII 

simply,  unless  it  is  good  in  all  those  ways:  since  evil  results 
from  any  single  defect,  hut  good  from  the  complete  cause,  as 
Dionysius  says  (Div.  Nom.  iv.). 


Fifth  Article. 

whether  a  human  action  is  good  or  evil  in 
its  species  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  good  and  evil  in  moral  actions 
do  not  make  a  difference  of  species.  For  the  existence  of 
good  and  evil  in  actions  is  in  conformity  with  their  existence 
in  things,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  But  good  and  evil  do  not 
make  a  specific  difference  in  things;  for  a  good  man  is 
specifically  the  same  as  a  bad  man.  Therefore  neither  do 
they  make  a  specific  difference  in  actions. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  since  evil  is  a  privation,  it  is  a  non-being. 
But  non-being  cannot  be  a  difference,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  (Metaph.  iii.).  Since  therefore  the  difference 
constitutes  the  species,  it  seems  that  an  action  is  not  consti- 
tuted in  a  species  through  being  evil.  Consequently  good 
and  evil  do  not  diversify  the  species  of  human  actions. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  acts  that  differ  in  species  produce  different 
effects.  But  the  same  specific  effect  results  from  a  good 
and  from  an  evil  action:  thus  a  man  is  born  of  adulterous  or 
of  lawful  wedlock.  Therefore  good  and  evil  actions  do  not 
differ  in  species. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  actions  are  sometimes  said  to  be  good  or 
bad  from  a  circumstance,  as  stated  above  (A.  3).  But  since 
a  circumstance  is  an  accident,  it  does  not  give  an  action  its 
species.  Therefore  human  actions  do  not  differ  in  species 
on  account  of  their  goodness  or  malice. 

On  the  contrary,  According  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  ii.) 
like  habits  produce  like  actions.  But  a  good  and  a  bad  habit 
differ  in  species,  as  liberality  and  prodigahty.  Therefore 
also  good  and  bad  actions  differ  in  species. 

1  answer  that,  Every  action  derives  its  species  from  its 
object,  as  stated  above  (A.  2).     Hence  it  follows  that  a 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  219 

difference  of  object  causes  a  difference  of  species  in  actions. 
Now,  it  must  be  observed  that  a  difference  of  objects  causes 
a  difference  in  actions,  according  as  the  latter  are  referred  to 
one  active  principle,  which  does  not  cause  a  difference  in 
actions,  according  as  they  are  referred  to  another  active 
principle.  Because  nothing  accidental  constitutes  a  species, 
but  only  that  which  is  essential;  and  a  difference  of  object 
may  be  essential  in  reference  to  one  active  principle,  and 
accidental  in  reference  to  another.  Thus  to  know  colour 
and  to  know  sound,  differ  essentially  in  reference  to  sense, 
but  not  in  reference  to  the  intellect. 

Now  in  human  actions,  good  and  evil  are  predicated  in 
reference  to  the  reason;  because  as  Dionysius  says  {Div. 
Noni.  iv.),  the  good  of  man  is  to  he  in  accordance  with  reason, 
and  evil  is  to  he  against  reason.  For  that  is  good  for  a  thing 
which  suits  it  in  regard  to  its  form;  and  evil,  that  which  is 
against  the  order  of  its  form.  It  is  therefore  evident  that 
the  difference  of  good  and  evil  considered  in  reference  to  the 
object  is  an  essential  difference  in  relation  to  reason;  that 
is  to  say,  according  as  the  object  is  suitable  or  unsuitable  to 
reason.  Now  certain  actions  are  called  human  or  moral, 
inasmuch  as  they  proceed  from  the  reason.  Consequently  it 
is  evident  that  good  and  evil  diversify  the  species  in  human 
actions ;  since  essential  differences  cause  a  difference  of  species. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Even  in  natural  things,  good  and  evil,  inas- 
much as  something  is  according  to  nature,  and  something 
against  nature,  diversify  the  natural  species;  for  a  dead  body 
and  a  living  body  are  not  of  the  same  species.  In  like  manner, 
good,  inasmuch  as  it  is  in  accord  with  reason,  and  evil,  in- 
asmuch as  it  is  against  reason,  diversify  the  moral  species. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Evil  implies  privation,  not  absolute,  but 
affecting  some  potentiality.  For  an  action  is  said  to  be  evil 
in  its  species,  not  because  it  has  no  object  at  all;  but  because 
it  has  an  object  in  disaccord  with  reason,  for  instance,  to 
appropriate  another's  property.  Wherefore  in  so  far  as  the 
object  is  something  positive,  it  can  constitute  the  species  of 
an  evil  act. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  conjugal  act  and  adultery,  as  compared 


220  QUESTION  XVIII 

to  reason,  differ  specifically  and  have  effects  specifically 
different;  because  the  one  deserves  praise  and  reward,  the 
other,  blame  and  punishment.  But  as  compared  to  the 
generative  power,  they  do  not  differ  in  species;  and  thus  they 
have  one  specific  effect. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  A  circumstance  is  sometimes  taken  as  the 
essential  difference  of  the  object,  as  compared  to  reason; 
and  then  it  can  specify  a  moral  act.  And  it  must  needs  be 
so  whenever  a  circumstance  transforms  an  action  from  good 
to  evil;  for  a  circumstance  would  not  make  an  action  evil, 
except  through  being  repugnant  to  reason. 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  an  action  has  the  species  of  good  or  evil 

from  its  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  good  and  evil  which  are 
from  the  end  do  not  diversify  the  species  of  actions.  For 
actions  derive  their  species  from  the  object.  But  the  end 
is  altogether  apart  from  the  object.  Therefore  the  good 
and  evil  which  are  from  the  end  do  not  diversify  the  species 
of  an  action. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  that  which  is  accidental  does  not  consti- 
tute the  species,  as  stated  above  (A.  5).  But  it  is  accidental 
to  an  action  to  be  ordained  to  some  particular  end;  for 
instance,  to  give  alms  from  vainglory.  Therefore  actions 
are  not  diversified  as  to  species,  according  to  the  good  and 
evil  which  are  from  the  end. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  acts  that  differ  in  species,  can  be  ordained 
to  the  same  end:  thus  to  the  end  of  vainglory,  actions  of 
various  virtues  and  vices  can  be  ordained.  Therefore  the 
good  and  evil  which  are  taken  from  the  end,  do  not  diversify 
the  species  of  action. 

On  the  contrary,  It  has  been  shown  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  3) 
that  human  actions  derive  their  species  from  the  end. 
Therefore  good  and  evil  in  respect  of  the  end,  diversify  the 
species  of  actions. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  221 

/  answer  that,  Certain  actions  are  called  human,  inasmuch 
as  they  are  voluntary,  as  stated  above  (Q.  L,  A.  i).  Now, 
in  a  voluntary  action,  there  is  a  twofold  action,  viz.,  the 
interior  action  of  the  will,  and  the  external  action :  and  each 
of  these  actions  has  its  object.  The  end  is  properly  the 
object  of  the  interior  act  of  the  will:  while  the  object  of  the 
external  action,  is  that  on  which  the  action  is  brought  to 
bear.  Therefore  just  as  the  external  action  takes  its  species 
from  the  object  on  which  it  bears:  so  the  interior  act  of  the 
will  takes  its  species  from  the  end,  as  from  its  own  proper 
object. 

Now  that  which  is  on  the  part  of  the  will  is  formal  in 
regard  to  that  which  is  on  the  part  of  the  external  action: 
because  the  will  uses  the  limbs  to  act  as  instruments;  nor 
have  external  actions  any  measure  of  morality,  save  in  so 
far  as  they  are  voluntary.  Consequently  the  species  of  a 
human  act  is  considered  formally  with  regard  to  the  end, 
but  materially  with  regard  to  the  object  of  the  external 
action.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic  v.)  that  he  who 
steals  that  he  may  commit  adultery,  is,  strictly  speaking,  more 
adulterer  than  thief. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  end  also  has  the  character  of  an  object, 
as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  it  is  accidental  to  the  external 
action  to  be  ordained  to  some  particular  end,  it  is  not 
accidental  to  the  interior  act  of  the  will,  which  act  is  com  - 
pared  to  the  external  act,  as  form  to  matter. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  When  many  actions,  differing  in  species, 
are  ordained  to  the  same  end,  there  is  indeed  a  diversity  of 
species  on  the  part  of  the  external  actions;  but  unity  of 
species  on  the  part  of  the  internal  action. 


222  ^  QUESTION  XVIII 

Seventh  Article. 

whether  the  species  derived  from  the  end  is  con- 
tained under  the  species  derived  from  the  object, 
as  under  its  genus,  or  conversely  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  species  of  goodness  derived 
from  the  end  is  contained  under  the  species  of  goodness 
derived  from  the  object,  as  a  species  is  contained  under  its 
genus;  for  instance,  when  a  man  commits  a  theft  in  order 
to  give  an  alms.  For  an  action  takes  its  species  from  its 
object,  as  stated  above  (AA.  2,  6).  But  it  is  impossible  for 
a  thing  to  be  contained  under  another  species,  if  this  species 
be  not  contained  under  the  proper  species  of  that  thing; 
because  the  same  thing  cannot  be  contained  in  different 
species  that  are  not  subordinate  to  one  another.  Therefore 
the  species  which  is  taken  from  the  end,  is  contained  under 
the  species  which  is  taken  from  the  object. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  last  difference  always  constitutes 
the  most  specific  species.  But  the  difference  derived  from 
the  end  seems  to  be  come  after  the  difference  derived  from 
the  object:  because  the  end  is  something  last.  Therefore 
the  species  derived  from  the  end,  is  contained  under  the 
species  derived  from  the  object,  as  its  most  specific  species. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  more  formal  a  difference  is,  the  more 
specific  it  is:  because  difference  is  compared  to  genus,  as 
form  to  matter.  But  the  species  derived  from  the  end,  is 
more  formal  than  that  which  is  derived  from  the  object,  as 
stated  above  (A.  6).  Therefore  the  species  derived  from 
the  end  is  contained  under  the  species  derived  from  the 
object,  as  the  most  specific  species  is  contained  under  the 
subaltern  genus. 

On  the  contrary,  Each  genus  has  its  determinate  differ- 
ences. But  an  action  of  one  same  species  on  the  part  of 
its  object,  can  be  ordained  to  an  infinite  number  of  ends: 
for  instance,  theft  can  be  ordained  to  an  infinite  number  of 
good  and  bad  ends.     Therefore  the  species  derived  from  the 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  223 

end  is  not  contained  under  the  species  derived  from  the 
object,  as  under  its  genus. 

I  answer  that,  The  object  of  the  external  act  can  stand  in 
a  twofold  relation  to  the  end  of  the  will:  first,  as  being  of 
itself  ordained  thereto;  thus  to  fight  well  is  of  itself  ordained 
to  victory;  secondly,  as  being  ordained  thereto  accidentally; 
thus  to  take  what  belongs  to  another  is  ordained  accident- 
ally to  the  giving  of  alms.  Now  the  differences  that  divide 
a  genus,  and  constitute  the  species  of  that  genus,  must,  as 
the  Philosopher  says  (Metaph.  vii.),  belong  to  that  genus  of 
themselves :  and  if  they  belong  to  it  accidentally,  the  division 
is  incorrect:  as,  if  one  were  to  say:  Animals  are  divided  into 
rational  and  irrational ;  and  the  irrational  into  animals  with 
wings,  and  animals  without  wings  ;  for  winged  and  wingless 
are  not  essential  determinations  of  the  irrational  being. 
But  the  following  division  would  be  correct:  Some  animals 
have  feet,  some  have  no  feet :  and  of  those  that  have  feet,  some 
have  two  feet,  some  four,  some  many  :  because  the  latter 
division  is  an  essential  determination  of  the  former.  Accord- 
ingly when  the  object  is  not  of  itself  ordained  to  the  end, 
the  specific  difference  derived  from  the  object  is  not  an  essen- 
tial determination  of  the  species  derived  from  the  end,  nor 
is  the  reverse  the  case.  Wherefore  one  of  these  species  is 
not  under  the  other;  but  then  the  moral  action  is  contained 
under  two  species  that  are  disparate,  as  it  were.  Conse- 
quently we  say  that  he  that  commits  adultery  for  the  sake 
of  theft,  is  guilty  of  a  twofold  malice  in  one  action. — On 
the  other  hand,  if  the  object  be  of  itself  ordained  to  the  end, 
one  of  these  differences  is  an  essential  determination  of  the 
other.  Wherefore  one  of  these  species  will  be  contained 
under  the  other. 

It  remains  to  be  considered  which  of  the  two  is  contained 
under  the  other.  In  order  to  make  this  clear,  we  must  first 
of  all  observe  that  the  more  particular  the  form  is  from 
which  a  difference  is  taken,  the  more  specific  is  the  differ- 
ence. Secondly,  that  the  more  universal  an  agent  is,  the 
more  universal  a  form  does  it  cause.  Thirdly,  that  the 
more  remote  an  end  is.  the  more  universal  the  agent  to 


224  QUESTION  XVIII 

which  it  corresponds;  thus  victory,  which  is  the  last  end  of 
the  army,  is  the  end  intended  by  the  commander  in  chief; 
while  the  command  of  this  or  that  regiment  is  the  end  in- 
tended by  one  of  the  lower  officers.  From  all  this  it  follows 
that  the  specific  difference  derived  from  the  end,  is  more 
general;  and  that  the  difference  derived  from  an  object 
which  of  itself  is  ordained  to  that  end,  is  a  specific  difference 
in  relation  to  the  former.  For  the  will,  the  proper  object 
of  which  is  the  end,  is  the  universal  mover  in  respect  of  all 
the  powers  of  the  soul,  the  proper  objects  of  which  are  the 
objects  of  their  particular  acts. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  One  and  the  same  thing,  considered  in  its 
substance,  cannot  be  in  two  species,  one  of  which  is  not 
subordinate  to  the  other.  But  in  respect  of  those  things 
which  are  superadded  to  the  substance,  one  thing  can  be 
contained  under  different  species.  Thus  one  and  the  same 
fruit,  as  to  its  colour,  is  contained  under  one  species,  i.e.,  a 
white  thing:  and,  as  to  its  perfume,  under  the  species  of 
sweet-smelling  things.  In  like  manner  an  action  which,  as 
to  its  substance,  is  in  one  natural  species,  considered  in 
respect  of  the  moral  conditions  that  are  added  to  it,  can 
belong  to  two  species,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  end  is  last  in  execution;  but  first  in  the 
intention  of  the  reason,  in  regard  to  which  moral  actions 
receive  their  species. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Difference  is  compared  to  genus  as  form  to 
matter,  inasmuch  as  it  actualizes  the  genus.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  genus  is  considered  as  more  formal  than  the 
species,  inasmuch  as  it  is  something  more  absolute  and  less 
contracted.  Wherefore  also  the  parts  of  a  definition  are 
reduced  to  the  genus  of  formal  cause,  as  is  stated  in  Phys.  ii. 
And  in  this  sense  the  genus  is  the  formal  cause  of  the  species; 
and  so  much  the  more  formal,  as  it  is  more  universal. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  225 

Eighth  Article, 
whether  any  action  is  indifferent  in  its  species  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  no  action  is  indifferent  in  its 
species.  For  evil  is  the  privation  of  good,  according  to 
Augustine  {Enchirid.  41).  But  privation  and  habit  are 
immediate  contraries,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Categor. 
viii.).  Therefore  there  is  no  such  thing  as  an  action  that 
is  indifferent  in  its  species,  as  though  it  were  between  good 
and  evil. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  human  actions  derive  their  species  from 
their  end  or  object,  as  stated  above  (Q.  VI.,  AA.  i,  3).  Bat 
every  end  and  every  object  is  either  good  or  bad.  There- 
fore every  human  action  is  good  or  evil  according  to  its 
species. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  as  stated  above  (A.  i),  an  action  is  said 
to  be  good,  when  it  has  its  due  complement  of  goodness; 
and  evil,  when  it  lacks  that  complement.  But  every  action 
must  needs  either  have  the  entire  plenitude  of  its  goodness, 
or  lack  it  in  some  respect.  Therefore  every  action  must 
needs  be  either  good  or  bad  in  its  species,  and  none  is 
indifferent. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Serni.  Dom.  in 
Mont,  ii.),  that  there  are  certain  deeds  of  a  middle  kind,  which 
can  be  done  with  a  good  or  evil  mind,  of  which  it  is  rash  to 
form  a  judgment.  Therefore  some  actions  are  indifferent 
according  to  their  species. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (AA.  2,  5),  every  action 
takes  its  species  from  its  object;  while  human  action,  which 
is  called  moral,  takes  its  species  from  the  object,  in  relation 
to  the  principle  of  human  actions,  which  is  the  reason. 
Wherefore  if  the  object  of  an  action  includes  something  in 
accord  with  the  order  of  reason,  it  will  be  a  good  action 
according  to  its  species;  for  instance,  to  give  alms  to  a  person 
in  want.  On  the  other  hand,  if  it  includes  something 
repugnant  to  the  order  of  reason,   it  will  be  an  evil  act 

II.  I  15 


226  QUESTION  XVIII 

according  to  its  species;  for  instance,  to  steal,  which  is  to 
appropriate  what  belongs  to  another.  But  it  may  happen 
that  the  object  of  an  action  does  not  include  something 
pertaining  to  the  order  of  reason;  for  instance,  to  pick  up  a 
straw  from  the  ground,  to  walk  in  the  fields,  and  the  like: 
and  such  actions  are  indifferent  according  to  their  species. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Privation  is  twofold.  One  is  privation  as 
a  result  {privatum  esse),  and  this  leaves  nothing,  but  takes 
all  away:  thus  blindness  takes  away  sight  altogether;  dark- 
ness, light;  and  death,  life.  Between  this  privation  and 
the  contrary  habit,  there  can  be  no  medium  in  respect  of 
the  proper  subject. — The  other  is  privation  in  process 
(privari) :  thus  sickness  is  privation  of  health,  not  that  it 
takes  health  away  altogether,  but  that  it  is  a  kind  of  road 
to  the  entire  loss  of  health,  occasioned  by  death.  And 
since  this  sort  of  privation  leaves  something,  it  is  not 
always  the  immediate  contrary  of  the  opposite  habit.  In 
this  way  evil  is  a  privation  of  good,  as  Simplicius  says  in 
his  commentary  on  the  Categories:  because  it  does  not  take 
away  all  good,  but  leaves  some.  Consequently  there  can  be 
something  between  good  and  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Every  object  or  end  has  some  goodness  or 
malice,  at  least  natural  to  it :  but  this  does  not  imply  moral 
goodness  or  malice,  which  is  considered  in  relation  to  the 
reason,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj,  3.  Not  everything  belonging  to  an  action 
belongs  also  to  its  species.  Wherefore  although  an  action's 
specific  nature  may  not  contain  all  that  belongs  to  the  full 
complement  of  its  goodness,  it  is  not  therefore  an  action 
specifically  bad;  nor  is  it  specifically  good.  Thus  a  man  in 
regard  to  his  species  is  neither  virtuous  nor  wicked. 

Ninth  Article, 
whether  an  individual  action  can  be  indifferent  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Ninth  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  an  individual  action  can  be 
indifferent.     For  there  is  no  species  that  does  not,  or  cannot, 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  227 

contain  an  individual.  But  an  action  can  be  indifferent  in 
its  species,  as  stated  above  (A.  8).  Therefore  an  individual 
action  can  be  indifferent. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  individual  actions  cause  like  habits,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  ii.  But  a  habit  can  be  indifferent:  for  the 
Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iv.)  that  those  who  are  of  an  even 
temper  and  prodigal  disposition  are  not  evil;  and  yet  it  is 
evident  that  they  are  not  good,  since  they  depart  from 
virtue;  and  thus  they  are  indifferent  in  respect  of  a  habit. 
Therefore  some  individual  actions  are  indifferent. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  moral  good  belongs  to  virtue,  while 
moral  evil  belongs  to  vice.  But  it  happens  sometimes  that 
a  man  fails  to  ordain  a  specifically  indifferent  action  to  a 
vicious  or  virtuous  end.  Therefore  an  individual  action 
may  happen  to  be  indifferent. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  says  in  a  homily  (vi.  ijt  Evang.) : 
An  idle  word  is  one  that  lacks  either  the  usefulness  of  rectitude 
or  the  motive  of  just  necessity  or  pious  utility.  But  an  idle 
word  is  an  evil,  because  men  .  .  .  shall  render  an  account  of  it 
in  the  day  of  judgment  (Matth.  xii.  36) : — while  if  it  does  not 
lack  the  motive  of  just  necessity  or  pious  utility,  it  is  good. 
Therefore  every  word  is  either  good  or  bad.  For  the  same 
reason  every  other  action  is  either  good  or  bad.  Therefore 
no  individual  action  is  indifferent. 

/  answer  that,  It  happens  that  an  action  is  indifferent  in 
its  species;  but  considered  in  the  individual  it  is  good  or 
evil.  And  the  reason  of  this  is  because  a  moral  action,  as 
stated  above  (A.  3),  derives  its  goodness  not  only  from  its 
object,  whence  it  takes  its  species;  but  also  from  the  cir- 
cumstances, which  are  its  accidents,  as  it  were;  just  as 
something  belongs  to  a  man  by  reason  of  his  individual 
accidents,  which  does  not  belong  to  him  by  reason  of  his 
species.  And  every  individual  action  must  needs  have 
some  circumstance  that  makes  it  good  or  bad,  at  least  in 
respect  of  the  intention  of  the  end.  For  since  it  belongs  to 
the  reason  to  direct;  if  an  action  that  proceeds  from  deliber- 
ate reason  be  not  directed  to  the  due  end,  it  is,  by  that  fact 
alone,  repugnant  to  reason,   and  is  specifically  evil.     But 


228  QUESTION  XVIII 

if  it  be  directed  to  a  due  end  it  is  in  accord  with  reason; 
wherefore  it  is  specifically  good.  Now  it  must  needs  be 
either  directed  or  not  directed  to  a  due  end.  Consequently 
every  human  action  that  proceeds  from  deliberate  reason, 
if  it  be  considered  in  the  individual,  must  be  good  or  bad. 

If,  however,  it  does  not  proceed  from  deliberate  reason, 
but  from  some  act  of  the  imagination,  as  when  a  man 
strokes  his  beard,  or  moves  his  hand  or  foot;  such  an  action, 
properly  speaking,  is  not  moral  or  human;  since  this  depends 
on  the  reason.  Hence  it  will  be  indifferent,  as  standing 
apart  from  the  genus  of  moral  actions. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  For  an  action  to  be  indifferent  in  its  species 
can  be  understood  in  several  ways.  First  in  such  a  way  that 
its  indifference  is  drawn  from  its  very  species:  and  the 
objection  proceeds  on  this  line.  But  no  action  can  be  speci- 
fically indifferent  thus:  since  no  object  of  human  action  is 
such  that  it  cannot  be  directed  to  good  or  evil,  either 
through  its  end  or  through  a  circumstance. — Secondly, 
specific  indifference  of  an  action  may  be  due  to  the  fact  that 
as  far  as  its  species  is  concerned,  it  is  neither  good  nor  bad. 
Wherefore  it  can  be  made  good  or  bad  by  something  else. 
Thus  man,  as  far  as  his  species  is  concerned,  is  neither 
white  nor  black;  nor  is  it  a  condition  of  his  species  that  he 
should  not  be  black  or  white;  but  blackness  or  whiteness 
is  superadded  to  man  by  other  principles  than  those  of 
his  species. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  Philosopher  states  that  a  man  is  evil, 
properly  speaking,  if  he  be  hurtful  to  others.  And  accord- 
ingly he  says  that  the  prodigal  is  not  evil,  because  he  hurts 
none  save  himself.  And  the  same  applies  to  all  others 
who  are  not  hurtful  to  other  men.  But  we  say  here  that 
evil,  in  general,  is  all  that  is  repugnant  to  right  reason. 
And  in  this  sense  every  individual  action  is  either  good  or 
bad,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj,  3.  Whenever  an  end  is  intended  by  dehberate 
reason,  it  belongs  either  to  the  good  of  some  virtue,  or 
to  the  evil  of  some  vice.  Thus,  if  a  man's  action  is 
directed  to  the  support  or  repose  of  his  body,  it  is  also 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  229 

directed  to  the  good  of  virtue,  provided  he  direct  his  body 
itself  to  the  good  of  virtue.  The  same  clearly  applies  to 
other  actions. 

Tenth  Article. 

whether  a  circumstance  places  a  moral  action  in  the 
species  of  good  or  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Tenth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  circumstance  cannot  place  a 
moral  action  in  the  species  of  good  or  evil.  For  the  species 
of  an  action  is  taken  from  its  object.  But  circumstances 
differ  from  the  object.  Therefore  circumstances  do  not 
give  an  action  its  species. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  circumstances  are  as  accidents  in  rela- 
tion to  the  moral  action,  as  stated  above  (Q.  VII.,  A.  i). 
But  an  accident  does  not  constitute  the  species.  Therefore 
a  circumstance  does  not  constitute  a  species  of  good  or  evil. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  one  thing  is  not  in  several  species.  But 
one  action  has  several  circumstances.  Therefore  a  cir- 
cumstance does  not  place  a  moral  action  in  a  species  of 
good  or  evil. 

On  the  contrary,  Place  is  a  circumstance.  But  place 
makes  a  moral  action  to  be  in  a  certain  species  of  evil;  for 
theft  of  a  thing  from  a  holy  place  is  a  sacrilege.  Therefore 
a  circumstance  makes  a  moral  action  to  be  specifically  good 
or  bad. 

I  answer  that,  Just  as  the  species  of  natural  things  are 
constituted  by  their  natural  forms,  so  the  species  of  moral 
actions  are  constituted  by  forms  as  conceived  by  the  reason, 
as  is  evident  from  what  was  said  above  (A.  5).  But  since 
nature  is  determinate  to  one  thing,  nor  can  a  process  of 
nature  go  on  to  infinity,  there  must  needs  be  some  ultimate 
form  beyond  which  no  further  specific  difference  is  possible. 
Hence  it  is  that  in  natural  things,  that  which  is  accidental 
to  a  thing,  cannot  be  taken  as  a  difference  constituting  the 
species.  But  the  process  of  reason  is  not  fixed  to  one  par- 
ticular term,  for  at  any  point  it  can  still  proceed  further. 
And  consequently  that  which,  in  one  action,  is  taken  as  a 


230  QUESTION  XVIII 

circumstance  added  to  the  object  that  specifies  the  action, 
can  again  be  taken  by  the  directing  reason,  as  the  prin- 
cipal condition  of  the  object  that  determines  the  action's 
species.  Thus  to  appropriate  another's  property  is  specified 
by  reason  of  the  property  being  another's,  and  in  this  respect 
it  is  placed  in  the  species  of  theft;  and  if  we  consider  that 
action  also  in  its  bearing  on  place  or  time,  then  this  will 
be  an  additional  circumstance.  But  since  the  reason  can 
direct  as  to  place,  time,  and  the  like,  it  may  happen  that 
the  condition  as  to  time,  in  relation  to  the  object,  is  con- 
sidered as  being  in  disaccord  with  reason :  for  instance,  reason 
forbids  damage  to  be  done  to  a  holy  place.  Consequently 
to  steal  from  a  holy  place  has  an  additional  repugnance  to 
the  order  of  reason.  And  thus  place,  which  was  first  of  all 
considered  as  a  circumstance,  is  considered  here  as  the 
principal  condition  of  the  object,  and  as  itself  repugnant  to 
reason.  And  in  this  way,  whenever  a  circumstance  has  a 
special  relation  to  reason,  either  for  or  against,  it  must  needs 
specify  the  moral  action  whether  good  or  bad. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  A  circumstance,  in  so  far  as  it  specifies  an 
action,  is  considered  as  a  condition  of  the  object,  as  stated 
above,  and  as  being,  as  it  were,  a  specific  difference  thereof. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  circumstance,  so  long  as  it  is  but  a  cir- 
cumstance, does  not  specify  an  action,  since  thus  it  is  a 
mere  accident:  but  when  it  becomes  a  principal  condition 
of  the  object,  then  it  does  specify  the  action. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  It  is  not  every  circumstance  that  places  the 
moral  action  in  the  species  of  good  or  evil;  since  not  every 
circumstance  implies  accord  or  disaccord  with  reason  . 
Consequently,  although  one  action  may  have  many  cir- 
cumstances, it  does  not  follow  that  it  is  in  many  species. 
Nevertheless  there  is  no  reason  why  one  action  should  not 
be  in  several,  and  yet  disparate,  moral  species. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  HUMAN  ACTS  231 


Eleventh  Article. 

whether  every  circumstance  that  makes  an  action 
better  or  worse,  places  a  moral  action  in  a 
species  of  good  or  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eleventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  every  circumstance  relating 
to  good  or  evil,  specifies  an  action.  For  good  and  evil  are 
specific  differences  of  moral  actions.  Therefore  that  which 
causes  a  difference  in  the  goodness  or  malice  of  amoral  action, 
causes  a  specific  difference,  which  is  the  same  as  to  make  it 
differ  in  species.  Now  that  which  makes  an  action  better 
or  worse,  makes  it  differ  in  goodness  and  malice.  Therefore 
it  causes  it  to  differ  in  species.  Therefore  every  circum- 
stance that  makes  an  action  better  or  worse,  constitutes  a 
species. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  an  additional  circumstance  either  has  in 
itself  the  character  of  goodness  or  malice,  or  it  has  not.  If 
not,  it  cannot  make  the  action  better:  because  what  is  not 
good,  cannot  make  a  greater  good;  and  what  is  not  evil, 
cannot  make  a  greater  evil.  But  if  it  has  in  itself  the  char- 
acter of  good  or  evil,  for  this  very  reason  it  has  a  certain 
species  of  good  or  evil.  Therefore  every  circumstance  that 
makes  an  action  better  or  worse,  constitutes  a  new  species 
of  good  or  evil. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  according  to  Dionysius  (Div.  Nom.  iv.), 
evil  is  caused  by  each  single  defect.  Now  every  circumstance 
that  increases  malice,  has  a  special  defect.  Therefore  every 
such  circumstance  adds  a  new  species  of  sin.  And  for  the 
same  reason,  every  circumstance  that  increases  goodness, 
seems  to  add  a  new  species  of  goodness:  just  as  every  unity 
added  to  a  number  makes  a  new  species  of  number;  since 
the  good  consists  in  number,  weight,  and  measure  (P.  I., 
Q.  v.,  A.  5). 

On  the  contrary,  More  and  less  do  not  change  a  species. 
But  more  and  less  is  a  circumstance  of  additional  goodness 
or  malice.     Therefore  not  every  circumstance  that  makes 


232  QUESTION  XVIII 

a  moral  action  better  or  worse,  places  it  in  a  species  of  good 
or  evil. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  lo),  a  circumstance 
gives  the  species  of  good  or  evil  to  a  moral  action,  in  so  far 
as  it  regards  a  special  order  of  reason.  Now  it  happens 
sometimes  that  a  circumstance  does  not  regard  a  special 
order  of  reason  in  respect  of  good  or  evil,  except  on  the 
supposition  of  another  previous  circumstance,  from  which 
the  moral  action  takes  its  species  of  good  or  evil.  Thus  to 
take  something  in  a  large  or  small  quantity,  does  not  regard 
the  order  of  reason  in  respect  of  good  or  evil,  except  a  certain 
other  condition  be  presupposed,  from  which  the  action  takes 
its  malice  or  goodness;  for  instance,  if  what  is  taken  belongs 
to  another,  which  makes  the  action  to  be  discordant  with 
reason.  Wherefore  to  take  what  belongs  to  another  in  a 
large  or  small  quantity,  does  not  change  the  species  of  the 
sin.  Nevertheless  it  can  aggravate  or  diminish  the  sin. 
The  same  applies  to  other  evil  or  good  actions.  Conse- 
quently not  every  circumstance  that  makes  a  moral  action 
better  or  worse,  changes  its  species. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  In  things  which  can  be  more  or  less  intense, 
the  difference  of  more  or  less  does  not  change  the  species :  thus 
by  differing  in  whiteness  through  being  more  or  less  white 
a  thing  is  not  changed  in  regard  to  its  species  of  colour.  In 
like  manner  that  which  makes  an  action  to  be  more  or  less 
good  or  evil,  does  not  make  the  action  differ  in  species. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  circumstance  that  aggravates  a  sin,  or 
adds  to  the  goodness  of  an  action,  sometimes  has  no  good- 
ness or  malice  in  itself,  but  in  regard  to  some  other  condition 
of  the  action,  as  stated  above.  Consequently  it  does  not 
add  a  new  species,  but  adds  to  the  goodness  or  malice  de- 
rived from  this  other  condition  of  the  action. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  A  circumstance  does  not  always  involve  a 
distinct  defect  of  its  own;  sometimes  it  causes  a  defect  in 
reference  to  something  else.  In  like  manner  a  circumstance 
does  not  always  add  further  perfection,  except  in  reference 
to  something  else.  And,  for  as  much  as  it  does,  although  it 
may  add  to  the  goodness  or  malice,  it  does  not  always 
change  the  species  of  good  or  evil. 


QUESTION  XIX. 

OF  THE  GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  OF  THE  INTERIOR 
ACT  OF  THE  WILL. 

{In  Ten  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  goodness  of  the  interior  act  of 
the  will ;  under  which  head  there  are  ten  points  of  inquiry : 
(i)  Whether  the  goodness  of  the  will  depends  on  the  object  ? 
(2)  Whether  it  depends  on  the  object  alone  ?  (3)  Whether 
it  depends  on  reason  ?  (4)  Whether  it  depends  on  the  eternal 
law  ?  (5)  Whether  erring  reason  binds  ?  (6)  Whether 
the  will  is  evil  if  it  follows  the  erring  reason  against  the 
law  of  God  ?  (7)  Whether  the  goodness  of  the  will  in 
regard  to  the  means,  depends  on  the  intention  of  the  end  ? 

(8)  Whether  the  degree  of  goodness  or  malice  in  the  will 
depends  on  the  degree  of  good  or  evil  in  the  intention  ? 

(9)  Whether  the  goodness  of  the  will  depends  on  its  con- 
formity to  the  Divine  Will  ?  (10)  Whether  it  is  necessary 
for  the  human  will,  in  order  to  be  good,  to  be  conformed  to 
the  Divine  Will,  as  regards  the  thing  willed  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  the  goodness  of  the  will  depends 
on  the  object  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  goodness  of  the  will  does 
not  depend  on  the  object.  For  the  will  cannot  be  directed 
otherwise  than  to  what  is  good:  since  evil  is  outside  the  scope 
of  the  will,  as  Dionysius  says  {Div.  Nom.  iv.).  If  therefore 
the  goodness  of  the  will  depended  on  the  object,  it  would 
follow  that  every  act  of  the  will  is  good,  and  none  bad. 

233 


234  QUESTION  XIX 

Obj.  2.  Further,  good  is  first  of  all  in  the  end:  where- 
fore the  goodness  of  the  end,  as  such,  does  not  depend  on 
any  other.  But,  according  to  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  vi.), 
goodness  of  action  is  the  end,  hut  goodness  of  snaking  is 
never  the  end  :  because  the  latter  is  always  ordained  to  the 
thing  made,  as  to  its  end.  Therefore  the  goodness  of  the 
act  of  the  will  does  not  depend  on  any  object. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  such  as  a  thing  is,  such  does  it  make  a 
thing  to  be.  But  the  object  of  the  will  is  good,  by  reason  of 
the  goodness  of  nature.  Therefore  it  cannot  give  moral 
goodness  to  the  will.  Therefore  the  moral  goodness  of  the 
will  does  not  depend  on  the  object. 

On  the  contrary,  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  v.)  that 
justice  is  that  habit /row  which  men  wish  for  just  things  :  and 
accordingly,  virtue  is  a  habit  from  which  men  wish  for  good 
things.  But  a  good  will  is  «one  which  is  in  accordance  with 
virtue.  Therefore  the  goodness  of  the  will  is  from  the  fact 
that  a  man  wills  that  which  is  good. 

/  answer  that.  Good  and  evil  are  essential  differences  of 
the  act  of  the  will.  Because  good  and  evil  of  themselves 
regard  the  will;  just  as  truth  and  falsehood  regard  reason; 
the  act  of  which  is  divided  essentially  by  the  difference  of 
truth  and  falsehood,  for  as  much  as  an  opinion  is  said  to  be 
true  or  false.  Consequently  good  and  evil  will  are  acts 
differing  in  species.  Now  the  specific  difference  in  acts 
is  according  to  objects,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XVII.,  A.  5). 
Therefore  good  and  evil  in  the  acts  of  the  will  is  derived 
properly  from  the  objects. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  will  is  not  always  directed  to  what  is 
truly  good,  but  sometimes  to  the  apparent  good;  which  has 
indeed  some  measure  of  good,  but  not  of  a  good  that  is 
simply  suitable  to  be  desired.  Hence  it  is  that  the  act  of 
the  will  is  not  always  good,  but  sometimes  evil. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Although  an  action  can,  in  a  certain  way, 
be  man's  last  end;  nevertheless  such  action  is  not  an  act  of 
the  will,  as  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  i  ,ad  2). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Good  is  presented  to  the  will  as  its  object: 
and  in  so  far  as  it  is  in  accord  with  reason,  it  enters  the  moral 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  235 

order,  and  causes  moral  goodness  in  the  act  of  the  will: 
because  the  reason  is  the  principle  of  human  and  moral  acts, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XVIIL,  A.  5). 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  goodness  of  the  will  depends 
on  the  object  alone  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  goodness  of  the  will  does 
not  depend  on  the  object  alone.  For  the  end  has  a  closer 
relationship  to  the  will  than  to  any  other  power.  But  the 
acts  of  the  other  powers  derive  goodness  not  only  from  the 
object  but  also  from  the  end,  as  we  have  shown  above 
(Q.  XVIIL,  A.  4).  Therefore  the  act  also  of  the  will  derives 
goodness  not  only  from  the  object  but  also  from  the  end. 

Ohj.  2.  Farther,  the  goodness  of  an  action  is  derived  not 
only  from  the  object  but  also  from  the  circumstances,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  XVIIL,  A.  3).  But  according  to  the 
diversity  of  circumstances  there  may  be  diversity  of  good- 
ness and  malice  in  the  act  of  the  will :  for  instance,  if  a  man 
will,  when  he  ought,  where  he  ought,  as  much  as  he  ought, 
and  how  he  ought,  or  if  he  will  as  he  ought  not.  Therefore 
the  goodness  of  the  will  depends  not  only  on  the  object,  but 
also  on  the  circumstances. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  ignorance  of  circumstances  excuses 
malice  of  the  will,  as  stated  above  (Q.  VI.,  A.  8).  But  it 
would  not  be  so,  unless  the  goodness  or  malice  of  the  will 
depended  on  the  circumstances.  Therefore  the  goodness 
and  malice  of  the  will  depend  on  the  circumstances,  and  not 
only  on  the  object. 

On  the  contrary,  An  action  does  not  take  its  species  from 
the  circumstances  as  such,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XVIIL,  A.  10 
ad  2).  But  good  and  evil  are  specific  differences  of  the  act 
of  the  will,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  Therefore  the  goodness 
and  malice  of  the  will  depend,  not  on  the  circumstances,  but 
on  the  object  alone. 

I  answer  that,  In  every  genus,  the  more  a  thing  is  first,  the 


236  QUESTION  XIX 

more  simple  it  is,  and  the  fewer  the  principles  of  which  it 
consists:  thus  primary  bodies  are  simple.  Hence  it  is  to  be 
observed  that  the  first  things  in  every  genus,  are,  in  some 
way,  simple  and  consist  of  one  principle.  Now  the  principle 
of  the  goodness  and  malice  of  human  actions  is  taken  from  the 
act  of  the  will.  Consequently  the  goodness  and  malice  of 
the  act  of  the  will  depend  on  some  one  thing ;  while  the  good- 
ness and  malice  of  other  acts  may  depend  on  several  things. 

Now  that  one  thing  which  is  the  principle  in  each  genus, 
is  not  something  accidental  to  that  genus,  but  something 
essential  thereto :  because  whatever  is  accidental  is  reduced 
to  something  essential,  as  to  its  principle.  Therefore  the 
goodness  of  the  will's  act  depends  on  that  one  thing  alone, 
which  of  itself  causes  goodness  in  the  act;  and  that  one 
thing  is  the  object,  and  not  the  circumstances,  which  are 
accidents,  as  it  were,  of  the  act. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  end  is  the  object  of  the  will,  but  not  of 
the  other  powers.  Hence,  in  regard  to  the  act  of  the  will, 
the  goodness  derived  from  the  object,  does  not  differ  from 
that  which  is  derived  from  the  end,  as  they  differ  in  the  acts 
of  the  other  powers:  except  perhaps  accidentally,  in  so  far 
as  one  end  depends  on  another,  and  one  act  of  the  will  on 
another. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Given  that  the  act  of  the  will  is  fixed  on 
some  good,  no  circumstance  can  make  that  act  bad.  Con- 
sequently when  it  is  said  that  a~man  wills  a  good  when  he 
ought  not,  or  where  he  ought  not,  this  can  be  understood  in 
two  ways.  First,  so  that  this  circumstance  is  referred  to 
the  thing  willed.  And  thus  the  act  of  the  will  is  not  fixed 
on  something  good:  since  to  will  to  do  something  when  it 
ought  not  to  be  done,  is  not  to  will  something  good. 
Secondly,  so  that  the  circumstance  is  referred  to  the  act  of 
willing.  And  thus,  it  is  impossible  to  will  something  good 
when  one  ought  not  to,  because  one  ought  always  to  will 
what  is  good:  except,  perhaps,  accidentally,  in  so  far  as  a 
man  by  willing  some  particular  good,  is  prevented  from 
willing  at  the  same  time  another  good  which  he  ought  to 
will   at  that  time.     And  then  evil  results,   not  from  his 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  237 

willing  that  particular  good,  but  from  his  not  willing  the 
other.     The  same  applies  to  the  other  circumstances. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Ignorance  of  circumstances  excuses  malice  of 
the  will,  in  so  far  as  the  circumstance  affects  the  thing  willed : 
that  is  to  say,  in  so  far  as  a  man  ignores  the  circumstances  of 
the  act  which  he  wills. 

Third  Article. 

whether  the  goodness  of  the  will  depends 

on  reason  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  goodness  of  the  will  does 
not  depend  on  reason.  For  what  comes  first  does  not  depend 
on  what  follows.  But  the  good  belongs  to  the  will  before  it 
belongs  to  reason,  as  is  clear  from  what  has  been  said  above 
(Q.  IX.,  A.  i).  Therefore  the  goodness  of  the  will  does  not 
depend  on  reason. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vi.)  that  the 
goodness  of  the  practical  intellect  is  a  truth  that  is  in  con- 
formity with  right  desire.  But  right  desire  is  a  good  will. 
Therefore  the  goodness  of  the  practical  reason  depends  on 
the  goodness  of  the  will,  rather  than  conversely. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  mover  does  not  depend  on  that  which 
is  moved,  but  vice  versa.  But  the  will  moves  the  reason  and 
the  other  powers,  as  stated  above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  i).  Therefore 
the  goodness  of  the  will  does  not  depend  on  reason. 

On  the  contrary,  Hilary  says  [De  Trin.  x.) :  It  is  an  unruly 
will  that  persists  in  its  desires  in  opposition  to  reason.  But 
the  goodness  of  the  will  consists  in  not  being  unruly.  There- 
fore the  goodness  of  the  will  depends  on  its  being  subject  to 
reason. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (AA.  i,  2),  the  goodness  of 
the  will  depends  properly  on  the  object.  Now  the  will's 
object  is  proposed  to  it  by  reason.  Because  the  good 
understood  is  the  proportionate  object  of  the  will;  while 
sensitive  or  imaginary  good  is  proportionate  not  to  the  will 
but  to  the  sensitiv/e  appetite:  since  the  will  can  tend  to  the 


238  QUESTION  XIX 

universal  good,  which  reason  apprehends;  whereas  the 
sensitive  appetite  tends  only  to  the  particular  good,  appre- 
hended by  the  sensitive  power.  Therefore  the  goodness  of 
the  will  depends  on  reason,  in  the  same  way  as  it  depends  on 
the  object. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  good  considered  as  such,  i.e.,  as  appet- 
ible,  pertains  to  the  will  before  pertaining  to  the  reason. 
But  considered  as  true  it  pertains  to  the  reason,  before, 
under  the  aspect  of  goodness,  pertaining  to  the  will :  because 
the  will  cannot  desire  a  good  that  it  is  not  previously  appre- 
hended by  reason. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  Philosopher  speaks  there  of  the  practical 
intellect,  in  so  far  as  it  counsels  and  reasons  about  the 
means:  for  in  this  respect  it  is  perfected  by  prudence.  Now 
in  regard  to  the  means,  the  rectitude  of  the  reason  depends 
on  its  conformity  with  the  desire  of  a  due  end :  nevertheless 
the  very  desire  of  the  due  end  presupposes  on  the  part  of 
reason  a  right  apprehension  of  the  end. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  will  moves  the  reason  in  one  way:  the 
reason  moves  the  will  in  another,  viz.,  on  the  part  of  the 
object,  as  stated  above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  i). 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  goodness  of  the  will  depends 
on  the  eternal  law  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  the  goodness  of  the  human  will 
does  not  depend  on  the  eternal  law.  Because  to  one  thing 
there  is  one  rule  and  one  measure.  But  the  rule  of  the 
human  will,  on  which  its  goodness  depends,  is  right  reason. 
Therefore  the  goodness  of  the  will  does  not  depend  on  the 
eternal  law. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  a  measure  is  homogeneous  with  the  thing 
measured  (Metaph.  x.).  But  the  eternal  law  is  not  homo- 
geneous with  the  human  will.  Therefore  the  eternal  law 
cannot  be  the  measure  on  which  the  goodness  of  the  human 
will  depends. 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  239 

Obj.  3.  Further,  a  measure  should  be  most  certain.  But 
the  eternal  law  is  unknown  to  us.  Therefore  it  cannot  be 
the  measure  on  which  the  goodness  of  our  will  depends. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {Contra  Faust,  xxii.)  that 
sin  is  a  deed,  word  or  desire  against  the  eternal  law.  But 
malice  of  the  will  is  the  root  of  sin.  Therefore,  since  malice 
is  contrary  to  goodness,  the  goodness  of  the  will  depends  on 
the  eternal  law. 

/  answer  that,  Wherever  a  number  of  causes  are  subor- 
dinate to  one  another,  the  effect  depends  more  on  the  first 
than  on  the  second  cause:  since  the  second  cause  acts  only 
in  virtue  of  the  first.  Now  it  is  from  the  eternal  law,  which 
is  the  Divine  Reason,  that  human  reason  is  the  rule  of  the 
human  will,  from  which  the  human  will  derives  its  good- 
ness. Hence  it  is  written  (Ps.  iv.  6,  7) :  Many  say  :  Who 
showeth  us  good  things  ?  The  light  of  Thy  countenance,  0 
Lord,  is  signed  upon  us:  as  though  to  say:  'The  light  of 
our  reason  is  able  to  show  us  good  things,  and  guide  our 
will,  in  so  far  as  it  is  the  light  of  (i.e.,  derived  from)  Thy 
countenance.'  It  is  therefore  evident  that  the  goodness 
of  the  human  will  depends  on  the  eternal  law  much  more 
than  on  human  reason:  and  when  human  reason  fails  we 
must  have  recourse  to  the  Eternal  Reason. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  To  one  thing  there  are  not  several  proxi- 
mate measures;  but  there  can  be  several  measures  subor- 
dinate to  one  another. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  A  proximate  measure  is  homogeneous  with 
the  thing  measured;  a  remote  measure  is  not. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Although  the  eternal  law  is  unknown  to  us 
according  as  it  is  in  the  Divine  Mind:  nevertheless,  it  be- 
comes known  to  us  somewhat,  either  by  natural  reason 
which  is  derived  therefrom  as  its  proper  image;  or  by  some 
sort  of  additional  revelation. 


240  QUESTION  XIX 


Fifth  Article. 

whether  the  will  is^evil  when  it  is  at  variance 
with  erring  reason  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  not  evil  when  it  is 
at  variance  with  erring  reason.  Because  the  reason  is  the 
rule  of  the  human  will,  in  so  far  as  it  is  derived  from  the 
eternal  law,  as  stated  above  (A.  4).  But  erring  reason  is 
not  derived  from  the  eternal  law.  Therefore  erring  reason 
is  not  the  rule  of  the  human  will.  Therefore  the  will  is  not 
evil,  if  it  be  at  variance  with  erring  reason. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  according  to  Augustine,  the  command 
of  a  lower  authority  does  not  bind  if  it  be  contrary  to  the 
command  of  a  higher  authority :  for  instance,  if  a  provincial 
governor  command  something  that  is  forbidden  by  the 
emperor.  But  erring  reason  sometimes  proposes  what  is 
against  the  command  of  a  higher  power,  namely,  God 
Whose  power  is  supreme.  Therefore  the  decision  of  an 
erring  reason  does  not  bind.  Consequently  the  will  is  not 
evil  if  it  be  at  variance  with  erring  reason. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  every  evil  will  is  reducible  to  some  species 
of  malice.  But  the  will  that  is  at  variance  with  erring 
reason  is  not  reducible  to  some  species  of  malice.  For 
instance,  if  a  man's  reason  err  in  telling  him  to  commit 
fornication,  his  will  in  not  willing  to  do  so,  cannot  be  reduced 
to  any  species  of  malice.  Therefore  the  will  is  not  evil  when 
it  is  at  variance  with  erring  reason. 

On  the  contrary,  As  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  LXXIX., 
A.  13),  conscience  is  nothing  else  than  the  application  of 
knowledge  to  some  action.  Now  knowledge  is  in  the 
reason.  Therefore  when  the  will  is  at  variance  with  erring 
reason,  it  is  against  conscience.  But  every  such  will  is 
evil;  for  it  is  written  (Rom.  xiv.  23) :  All  that  is  not  of  faith — 
i.e.,  all  that  is  against  conscience — is  sin.  Therefore  the 
will  is  evil  when  it  is  at  variance  with  erring  reason. 

/  answer  that,  Since  conscience  is  a  kind  of  dictate  of  the 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  241 

reason  (for  it  is  an  application  of  knowledge  to  action,  as 
was  stated  in  the  First  Part,  Q.  LXXIX.,  A.  13),  to  inquire 
whether  the  will  is  evil  when  it  is  at  variance  with  erring 
reason,  is  the  same  as  to  inquire  whether  an  erring  con- 
science hinds.  On  this  matter,  some  distinguished  three 
kinds  of  actions:  for  some  are  good  generically,  some  are 
indifferent;  some  are  evil  generically.  And  they  say  that 
if  reason  or  conscience  tell  us  to  do  something  which  is  good 
generically,  there  is  no  error:  and  in  like  manner  if  it  tell 
us  not  to  do  something  which  is  evil  generically;  since  it 
is  the  same  reason  that  prescribes  what  is  good  and  forbids 
what  is  evil.  On  the  other  hand  if  a  man's  reason  or 
conscience  tell  him  that  he  is  bound  by  precept  to  do  what 
is  evil  in  itself;  or  that  what  is  good  in  itself,  is  forbidden, 
then  his  reason  or  conscience  errs.  In  like  manner  if  a 
man's  reason  or  conscience  tell  him,  that  what  is  indifferent 
in  itself,  for  instance  to  raise  a  straw  from  the  ground,  is 
forbidden  or  commanded,  his  reason  or  conscience  errs. 
They  say,  therefore,  that  reason  or  conscience  when  erring 
in  matters  of  indifference,  either  by  commanding  or  by  for- 
bidding them,  binds:  so  that  the  will  which  is  at  variance 
with  that  erring  reason  is  evil  and  sinful.  But  they  say 
that  when  reason  or  conscience  errs  in  commanding  what  is 
evil  in  itself,  or  in  forbidding  what  is  good  in  itself,  it  does 
not  bind;  wherefore  in  such  cases  the  will  which  is  at  variance 
with  erring  reason  or  conscience  is  not  evil. 

But  this  is  unreasonable.  For  in  matters  of  indifference, 
the  will  that  is  at  variance  with  erring  reason  or  conscience, 
is  evil  in  some  way  on  account  of  the  object,  on  which  the 
goodness  or  malice  of  the  will  depends;  not  indeed  on 
account  of  the  object  according  as  it  is  in  its  own  nature  ; 
but  according  as  it  is  accidentally  apprehended  by  reason 
as  something  evil  to  do  or  to  avoid.  And  since  the  object 
of  the  will  is  that  which  is  proposed  by  the  reason,  as  stated 
above  (A.  3),  from  the  very  fact  that  a  thing  is  proposed 
by  the  reason  as  being  evil,  the  will  by  tending  thereto 
becomes  evil.  And  this  is  the  case  not  only  in  indifferent 
matters,  but  also  in  those  that  are  good  or  evil  in  themselves. 

II.  I  16 


242  QUESTION  XIX 

For  not  only  indifferent  matters  can  receive  the  character 
of  goodness  or  malice  accidentally;  but  also  that  which  is 
good,  can  receive  the  character  of  evil,  or  that  which  is  evil, 
can  receive  the  character  of  goodness,  on  account  of  the 
reason  apprehending  it  as  such.  For  instance,  to  refrain 
from  fornication  is  good :  yet  the  will  does  not  tend  to  this 
good  except  in  so  far  as  it  is  proposed  by  the  reason.  If 
therefore,  the  erring  reason  propose  it  as  an  evil,  the  will 
tends  to  it  as  to  something  evil.  Consequently  the  will  is 
evil,  because  it  wills  evil,  not  indeed  that  which  is  evil  in 
itself,  but  that  which  is  evil  accidentally,  through  being 
apprehended  as  such  by  the  reason.  In  like  manner,  to 
believe  in  Christ  is  good  in  itself,  and  necessary  for  salva- 
tion: but  the  will  does  not  tend  thereto,  except  inasmuch 
as  it  is  proposed  by  the  reason.  Consequently  if  it  be 
proposed  by  the  reason  as  something  evil,  the  will  tends  to 
it  as  to  something  evil:  not  as  if  it  were  evil  in  itself,  but 
because  it  is  evil  accidentally,  through  the  apprehension  of 
the  reason.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vii.)  that 
properly  speaking  the  incontinent  man  is  one  who  does  not 
follow  right  reason  ;  hut  accidentally ,  he  is  also  one  who  does 
not  follow  false  reason.  We  must  therefore  conclude  that, 
absolutely  speaking,  every  will  at  variance  with  reason, 
whether  right  or  erring,  is  always  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Although  the  judgment  of  an  erring  reason 
is  not  derived  from  God,  yet  the  erring  reason  puts  forward 
its  judgment  as  being  true,  and  consequently  as  being 
derived  from  God,  from  Whom  is  all  truth. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  saying  of  Augustine  holds  good  when  it 
is  known  that  the  inferior  authority  prescribes  something 
contrary  to  the  command  of  the  higher  authority.  But  if 
a  man  were  to  believe  the  command  of  the  proconsul  to  be 
the  command  of  the  emperor,  in  scorning  the  command  of 
the  proconsul  he  would  scorn  the  command  of  the  emperor. 
In  like  manner  if  a  man  were  to  know  that  human  reason 
was  dictating  something  contrary  to  God's  commandment, 
he  would  not  be  bound  to  abide  by  reason:  but  then  reason 
would  not  be  entirely  erroneous.     But  when  erring  reason 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  243 

proposes  something  as  being  commanded  by  God,  then  to 
scorn  the  dictate  of  reason  is  to  scorn  the  commandment  of 
God. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Whenever  reason  apprehends  something  as 
evil,  it  apprehends  it  under  some  species  of  evil;  for  instance, 
as  being  something  contrary  to  a  divine  precept,  or  as  giving 
scandal,  or  for  some  suchlike  reason.  And  then  that  evil 
is  reduced  to  that  species  of  malice. 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  the  will  is  good  when  it  abides  by  erring 

REASON  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  will  is  good  when  it  abides 
by  erring  reason.  For  just  as  the  will,  when  at  variance 
with  the  reason,  tends  to  that  which  reason  judges  to  be 
evil;  so,  when  in  accord  with  the  reason,  it  tends  to  what 
reason  judges  to  be  good.  But  the  will  is  evil  when  it  is  at 
variance  with  reason,  even  when  erring.  Therefore  even 
when  it  abides  by  erring  reason,  the  will  is  good. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  will  is  always  good,  when  it  abides  by 
the  commandment  of  God  and  the  eternal  law.  But  the 
eternal  law  and  God's  commandment  are  proposed  to  us  by 
the  apprehension  of  the  reason,  even  when  it  errs.  There- 
fore the  will  is  good,  even  when  it  abides  by  erring  reason. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  will  is  evil  when  it  is  at  variance  with 
erring  reason.  If,  therefore,  the  will  is  evil  also  when  it 
abides  by  erring  reason,  it  seems  that  the  will  is  always  evil 
when  in  conjunction  with  erring  reason:  so  that  in  such  a 
case  a  man  would  be  in  two  minds,  and,  of  necessity,  would 
sin:  which  is  unreasonable.  Therefore  the  will  is  good 
when  it  abides  by  erring  reason. 

On  the  contrary,  The  will  of  those  who  slew  the  apostles 
was  evil.  And  yet  it  was  in  accord  with  their  erring  reason, 
according  to  John  xvi.  2:  The  hour  cometh,  that  whosoever 
killeth  you,  will  think  that  he  doth  a  service  to  God.  Therefore 
the  will  can  be  evil,  when  it  abides  by  erring  reason. 


244  QUESTION  XIX 

/  answer  that,  Whereas  the  previous  question  is  the  same 
as  inquiring  whether  an  erring  conscience  hinds ;  so  this 
question  is  the  same  as  inquiring  whether  an  erring  con- 
science excuses.  Now  this  question  depends  on  what  has 
been  said  above  about  ignorance.  For  it  was  said  (Q.  VI., 
A.  8)  that  ignorance  sometimes  causes  an  act  to  be  in- 
voluntary, and  sometimes  not.  And  since  moral  good  and 
evil  consist  in  action  in  so  far  as  it  is  voluntary,  as  was 
stated  above  (A.  2) ;  it  is  evident  that  when  ignorance  causes 
an  act  to  be  involuntary,  it  takes  away  the  species  of  moral 
good  and  evil;  but  not,  when  it  does  not  cause  the  act  to 
be  involuntary.  Again,  it  has  been  stated  above  (Q.  VI., 
A.  8)  that  when  ignorance  is  in  any  way  willed,  either 
directly  or  indirectly,  it  does  not  cause  the  act  to  be  in- 
voluntary. And  I  call  that  ignorance  directly  voluntary, 
to  which  the  act  of  the  will  tends:  and  that,  indirectly 
voluntary,  which  is  due  to  negligence,  by  reason  of  a  man 
not  wishing  to  know  what  he  ought  to  know,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  VI.,  A.  8). 

If  then  reason  or  conscience  err  with  an  error  that  is 
voluntary,  either  directly,  or  through  negligence,  so  that 
one  errs  about  what  one  ought  to  know;  then  such  an  error 
of  reason  or  conscience  does  not  excuse  the  will,  that 
abides  by  that  erring  reason  or  conscience,  from  being  evil. 
But  if  the  error  arise  from  ignorance  of  some  circumstance, 
and  without  any  negligence,  so  that  it  cause  the  act  to  be 
involuntary,  then  that  error  of  reason  or  conscience  excuses 
the  will,  that  abides  by  that  erring  reason,  from  being  evil. 
For  instance,  if  erring  reason  tell  a  man  that  he  should  go 
to  another  man's  wife,  the  will  that  abides  by  that  erring 
reason  is  evil;  since  this  error  arises  from  ignorance  of  the 
Divine  Law,  which  he  is  bound  to  know.  But  if  a  man's 
reason  errs  in  mistaking  another  for  his  wife,  and  if  he 
wish  to  give  her  her  right  when  she  asks  for  it,  his  will  is 
excused  from  being  evil:  because  this  error  arises  from 
ignorance  of  a  circumstance,  which  ignorance  excuses,  and 
causes  the  act  to  be  involuntary. 

Reply  Ohj.   i.  As  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Nom.  vi.),  good 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  245 

results  from  the  entire  cause,  evil  from  each  particular  defect. 
Consequently,  in  order  that  the  thing  to  which  the  will 
tends  be  called  evil,  it  suffices,  either  that  it  be  evil  in  itself, 
or  that  it  be  apprehended  as  evil.  But  in  order  for  it  to 
be  good,  it  must  be  good  in  both  ways. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  eternal  law  cannot  err,  but  human 
reason  can.  Consequently  the  will  that  abides  by  human 
reason,  is  not  always  right,  nor  is  it  always  in  accord  with 
the  eternal  law. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Just  as  in  syllogistic  arguments,  granted 
one  absurdity,  others  must  needs  follow;  so  in  moral  matters, 
given  one  absurdity,  others  must  follow  too.  Thus  suppose 
a  man  to  seek  vainglory,  he  will  sin,  whether  he  does  his 
duty  for  vainglory,  or  whether  he  omit  to  do  it.  Nor  is  he 
in  two  minds  about  the  matter:  because  he  can  put  aside 
his  evil  intention.  In  like  manner,  suppose  a  man's  reason 
or  conscience  to  err  through  inexcusable  ignorance,  then 
evil  must  needs  result  in  the  will.  Nor  is  this  man  in 
two  minds:  because  he  can  lay  aside  his  error,  since  his 
ignorance  is  vincible  and  voluntary. 

Seventh  Article. 

whether  the  goodness  of  the  will,  as  regards  the 
means,  depends  on  the  intention  of  the  end  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  goodness  of  the  will  does 
not  depend  on  the  intention  of  the  end.  For  it  has  been 
stated  above  (A.  2)  that  the  goodness  of  the  will  depends 
on  the  object  alone.  But  as  regards  the  means,  the  object 
of  the  will  is  one  thing,  and  the  end  intended  is  another. 
Therefore  in  such  matters  the  goodness  of  the  will  does  not 
depend  on  the  intention  of  the  end. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  to  wish  to  keep  God's  commandment, 
belongs  to  a  good  will.  But  this  can  be  referred  to  an  evil 
end,  for  instance  to  vainglory  or  covetousness,  by  willing  to 
obey  God  for  the  sake  of  temporal  gain.  Therefore  the  good- 
ness of  the  will  does  not  depend  on  the  intention  of  the  end. 


246  QUESTION  XIX 

Ob],  3.  Further,  just  as  good  and  evil  diversify  the  will, 
so  do  they  diversify  the  end.  But  malice  of  the  will  does 
not  depend  on  the  malice  of  the  end  intended ;  since  a  man 
who  wills  to  steal  in  order  to  give  alms,  has  an  evil  will, 
although  he  intends  a  good  end.  Therefore  neither  does  the 
goodness  of  the  will  depend  on  the  goodness  of  the  end 
intended. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Confess,  ix.)  that  God 
rewards  the  intention.  But  God  rewards  a  thing  because  it 
is  good.  Therefore  the  goodness  of  the  will  depends  on 
the  intention  of  the  end. 

/  answer  that,  The  intention  may  stand  in  a  twofold 
relation  to  the  act  of  the  will;  first,  as  preceding  it,  secondly 
as  following*  it.  The  intention  precedes  the  act  of  the  will 
causally,  when  we  will  something  because  we  intend  a 
certain  end.  And  then  the  order  to  the  end  is  considered 
as  the  reason  of  the  goodness  of  the  thing  willed:  for  in- 
stance, when  a  man  wills  to  fast  for  God's  sake;  because  the 
act  of  fasting  is  specifically  good  from  the  very  fact  that  it  is 
done  for  God's  sake.  Wherefore,  since  the  goodness  of  the 
will  depends  on  the  goodness  of  the  thing  willed,  as  stated 
above  (AA.  i,  2),  it  must,  of  necessity,  depend  on  the  in- 
tention of  the  end. 

On  the  other  hand,  intention  follows  the  act  of  the  will, 
when  it  is  added  to  a  preceding  act  of  the  will :  for  instance, 
a  man  may  will  to  do  something,  and  may  afterwards  refer 
it  to  God.  And  then  the  goodness  of  the  previous  act  of 
the  will  does  not  depend  on  the  subsequent  intention,  except 
in  so  far  as  that  act  is  repeated  with  the  subsequent 
intention. 

Reply  Ob'j.  i.  When  the  intention  is  the  cause  of  the  act 
of  willing,  the  order  to  the  end  is  considered  as  the  reason  of 
the  goodness  of  the  object,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  act  of  the  will  cannot  be  said  to  be  good, 

if  an  evil  intention  is  the  cause  of  willing.     For  when  a  man 

wills  to  give  an  alms  for  the  sake  of  vainglory,  he  wills  that 

which  is  good  in  itself,  under  a  species  of  evil;  and  there- 

*  Leonine  ed. — accompanying. 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  247 

fore,  as  willed  by  him,  it  is  evil.  Wherefore  his  will  is 
evil.  If,  however,  the  intention  is  subsequent  to  the  act 
of  the  will,  then  the  latter  may  be  good:  and  the  intention 
does  not  spoil  that  act  of  the  will  which  preceded,  but  that 
which  is  repeated. 

Refly  Ohj.  3.  x\s  we  have  already  stated  (A.  6  ad  i),  evil 
results  from  each  particular  defect,  hut  good  from  the  whole 
and  entire  cause.  Hence,  whether  the  will  tend  to  what 
is  evil  in  itself,  even  under  the  species  of  good ;  or  to  the  good 
under  the  species  of  evil,  it  will  be  evil  in  either  case.  But 
in  order  for  the  will  to  be  good,  it  must  tend  to  the  good 
under  the  species  of  good;  in  other  words,  it  must  will  the 
good  for  the  sake  of  the  good. 

Eighth  Article. 

whether  the  degree  of  goodness  or  malice  in  the 
will  depends  on  the  degree  of  good  or  evil  in 
the  intention  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  degree  of  goodness  in  the 
will  depends  on  the  degree  of  good  in  the  intention.  Be- 
cause on  Matth.  xii.  35  (Luke  vi.  45),  A  good  man  out  of  the 
good  treasure  of  his  heart,  hringeth  forth  that  which  is  good , 
the  gloss  says :  A  man  does  as  much  good  as  he  intends.  But 
the  intention  gives  goodness  not  only  to  the  external  action, 
but  also  to  the  act  of  the  will,  as  stated  above  (A.  7) . 
Therefore  the  goodness  of  a  man's  will  is  according  to  the 
goodness  of  his  intention. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  if  you  add  to  the  cause,  you  add  to  the 
effect.  But  the  goodness  of  the  intention  is  the  cause  of 
the  good  will.  Therefore  a  man's  will  is  good,  according  as 
his  intention  is  good. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  in  evil  actions,  a  man  sins  in  proportion 
to  his  intention:  for  if  a  man  were  to  throw  a  stone  with  a 
murderous  intention,  he  would  be  guilty  of  murder.  There- 
fore, for  the  same  reason,  in  good  actions,  the  will  is  good 
in  proportion  to  the  good  intended. 


248  QUESTION  XIX 

On  the  contrary,  The  intention  can  be  good,  while  the  will 
is  evil.  Therefore,  for  the  same  reason,  the  intention  can 
be  better,  and  the  will  less  good. 

/  answer  that,  In  regard  to  both  the  act,  and  the  inten- 
tion of  the  end,  we  may  consider  a  twofold  quantity:  one, 
on  the  part  of  the  object,  by  reason  of  a  man  wilHng  or 
doing  a  good  that  is  greater;  the  other,  taken  from  the 
intensity  of  the  act,  according  as  a  man  wills  or  acts  in- 
tensely; and  this  is  more  on  the  part  of  the  agent. 

If  then  we  speak  of  these  respective  quantities  from  the 
point  of  view  of  the  object,  it  is  evident  that  the  quantity 
in  the  act  does  not  depend  on  the  quantity  in  the  intention. 
With  regard  to  the  external  act  this  may  happen  in  two 
ways.  First,  through  the  object  that  is  ordained  to  the 
intended  end  not  being  proportionate  to  that  end:  for  in- 
stance, if  a  man  were  to  give  ten  pounds,  he  could  not  realize 
his  intention,  if  he  intended  to  buy  a  thing  worth  a  hundred 
pounds.  Secondly,  on  account  of  the  obstacles  that  may 
supervene  in  regard  to  the  exterior  action,  which  obstacles 
we  are  unable  to  remove :  for  instance,  a  man  intends  to  go 
to  Rome,  and  encounters  obstacles,  which  prevent  him 
from  going. — On  the  other  hand,  with  regard  to  the  in- 
terior act  of  the  will,  this  happens  in  only  one  way :  because 
the  interior  acts  of  the  will  are  in  our  power,  whereas  the 
external  actions  are  not.  But  the  will  can  will  an  object 
that  is  not  proportionate  to  the  intended  end :  and  thus  the 
will  that  tends  to  that  object  considered  absolutely,  is  not 
so  good  as  the  intention.  Yet  because  the  intention  also 
belongs,  in  a  way,  to  the  act  of  the  will, — inasmuch,  to  wit, 
as  it  is  the  reason  thereof ;  it  comes  to  pass  that  the  quantity 
of  goodness  in  the  intention  redounds  upon  the  act  of  the 
will ;  that  is  to  say,  in  so  far  as  the  will  wills  some  great  good 
for  an  end,  although  that  by  which  it  wills  to  gain  so  great  a 
good,  is  not  proportionate  to  that  good. 

But  if  we  consider  the  quantity  in  the  intention  and  in 
the  act,  according  to  their  respective  intensity,  then  the 
intensity  of  the  intention  redounds  upon  the  interior  act 
and  the  exterior  act  of  the  will:  since  the  intention  stands 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  249 

in  relation  to  them  as  a  kind  of  form,  as  is  clear  from  what 
was  said  above  (Q.  XIL,  A.  4;  Q.  XVIIL,  A.  6).  And  yet 
considered  materially,  while  the  intention  is  intense,  the 
interior  or  exterior  act  may  be  not  so  intense,  materially 
speaking:  for  instance,  when  a  man  does  not  will  with  as 
much  intensity  to  take  medicine  as  he  wills  to  regain  health. 
Nevertheless  the  very  fact  of  intending  health  intensely, 
redounds,  as  a  formal  principle,  upon  the  intense  volition 
of  medicine. 

We  must  observe,  however,  that  the  intensity  of  the 
interior  or  exterior  act,  may  be  referred  to  the  intention  as 
its  object:  as  when  a  man  intends  to  will  intensely,  or  to  do 
something  intensely.  And  yet  it  does  not  follow  that  he 
wills  or  acts  intensely :  because  the  quantity  of  goodness  in 
the  interior  or  exterior  act  does  not  depend  on  the  quantity 
of  the  good  intended,  as  was  shewn  above  (A.  7).  And 
hence  it  is  that  a  man  does  not  merit  as  much  as  he  intends 
to  merit :  because  the  quantity  of  merit  is  measured  by  the 
intensity  of  the  act,  as  we  shall  show  later  on  (Q.  XX.,  A.  4; 
Q.CXIV.,  A.4). 

Reply  Obj.  1.  This  gloss  speaks  of  good  as  in  the  estima- 
tion of  God,  Who  considers  principally  the  intention  of  the 
end.  Wherefore  another  gloss  says  on  the  same  passage 
that  the  treasure  of  the  heart  is  the  intention,  according  to 
which  God  judges  our  works.  For  the  goodness  of  the  inten- 
tion, as  stated  above,  redounds,  so  to  speak,  upon  the  good- 
ness of  the  will,  which  makes  even  the  external  act  to  be 
meritorious  in  God's  sight. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  goodness  of  the  intention  is  not  the 
whole  cause  of  a  good  will.  Hence  the  argument  does  not 
prove. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  mere  malice  of  the  intention  suffices  to 
make  the  will  evil:  and  therefore  too,  the  will  is  as  evil  as 
the  intention  is  evil.  But  the  same  reasoning  does  not 
apply  to  goodness,  as  stated  above  {ad  2) 


250  QUESTION  XIX 


Ninth  Article. 

whether  the  goodness  of  the  will  depends  on  its 
conformity  to  the  divine  will  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Ninth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  goodness  of  the  human  will 
does  not  depend  on  its  conformity  to  the  Divine  will.  Be- 
cause it  is  impossible  for  man's  will  to  be  conformed  to  the 
Divine  will;  as  appears  from  the  word  of  Isaias  (Iv.  9): 
As  the  heavens  are  exalted  above  the  earth,  so  are  My  ways 
exalted  above  your  ways,  and  My  thoughts  above  your  thoughts. 
If  therefore  goodness  of  the  will  depended  on  its  conformity 
to  the  Divine  will,  it  would  follow  that  it  is  impossible  for 
man's  will  to  be  good.     Which  is  inadmissible. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  just  as  our  wills  arise  from  the  Divine 
will,  so  does  our  knowledge  flow  from  the  Divine  know- 
ledge. But  our  knowledge  does  not  require  to  be  con- 
formed to  God's  knowledge;  since  God  knows  many  things 
that  we  know  not.  Therefore  there  is  no  need  for  our  will 
to  be  conformed  to  the  Divine  will. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  will  is  a  principle  of  action.  But  our 
action  cannot  be  conformed  to  God's.  Therefore  neither 
can  our  will  be  conformed  to  His. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Matth.  xxvi.  39):  Not  as  I 
will,  but  as  Thou  wilt :  which  words  He  said,  because  He 
wishes  man  to  be  upright  and  to  tend  to  God,  as  Augustine 
expounds  in  the  Enchiridion  {Enarr.  in  Ps.  xxxii. ;  serm.  i.). 
But  the  rectitude  of  the  will  is  its  goodness.  Therefore  the 
goodness  of  the  will  depends  on  its  conformity  to  the  Divine 
will. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  7),  the  goodness  of  the 
will  depends  on  the  intention  of  the  end.  Now  the  last 
end  of  the  human  will  is  the  Sovereign  Good,  namely,  God, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  8;  Q.  III.,  A.  i).  Therefore  the 
goodness  of  the  human  will  requires  it  to  be  ordained  to  the 
Sovereign  Good,  that  is,  to  God. 

Now  this  Good  is  primarily  and  essentially  compared  to 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  251 

the  Divine  will,  as  its  proper  object.  Again  that  which  is 
lirst  in  any  genus,  is  the  measure  and  rule  of  all  that  belongs 
to  that  genus.  Moreover,  everything  attains  to  rectitude 
and  goodness,  in  so  far  as  it  is  in  accord  with  its  proper 
measure.  Therefore  in  order  that  man's  will  be  good,  it 
needs  to  be  conformed  to  the  Divine  will. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  human  will  cannot  be  conformed  to  the 
will  of  God  so  as  to  equal  it,  but  only  so  as  to  imitate  it. 
In  like  manner  human  knowledge  is  conformed  to  the 
Divine  knowledge,  in  so  far  as  it  knows  truth:  and  human 
action  is  conformed  to  the  Divine,  in  so  far  as  it  is  becoming 
to  the  agent : — and  this  by  way  of  imitation,  not  by  way  of 
equality. 

From  the  above  may  be  gathered  the  replies  to  the 
Second  and  Third  Objections. 

Tenth  x\rti CLE. 

WHETHER  IT  IS  NECESSARY  FOR  THE  HUMAN  WILL,  IN  ORDER 
TO  BE  GOOD,  TO  BE  CONFORMED  TO  THE  DIVINE  WILL, 
AS  REGARDS  THE  THING  WILLED  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Tenth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  human  will  need  not  always 
be  conformed  to  the  Divine  will,  as  regards  the  thing  willed. 
For  we  cannot  will  what  we  know  not:  since  the  appre- 
hended good  is  the  object  of  the  will.  But  in  many  things 
we  know  not  what  God  wills.  Therefore  the  human  will  can- 
not be  conformed  to  the  Divine  will  as  to  the  thing  willed. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  God  wills  to  damn  the  man  whom  He 
foresees  about  to  die  in  mortal  sin.  If  therefore  man  were 
bound  to  conform  his  will  to  the  Divine  will,  in  the  point 
of  the  thing  willed,  it  would  follow  that  a  man  is  bound  to 
will  his  own  damnation.     Which  is  inadmissible. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  no  one  is  bound  to  will  what  is  against 
filial  piety.  But  if  man  were  to  will  what  God  wills,  this 
would  sometimes  be  contrary  to  filial  piety:  for  instance, 
when  God  wills  the  death  of  a  father;  if  his  son  were  to 
will  it  also,  it  would  be  against  filial  piety.     Therefore  man 


252  QUESTION  XIX 

is  not  bound  to  conform  his  will  to  the  Divine  will,  as  to  the 
thing  willed. 

On  the  contrary,  (i)  On  Ps.  xxxii.  i,  Praise  hecometh  the 
upright,  a  gloss  says:  That  man  has  an  upright  heart,  who 
wills  what  God  wills.  But  everyone  is  bound  to  have  an 
upright  heart.  Therefore  everyone  is  bound  to  will  what 
God  wills. 

(2)  Moreover,  the  will  takes  its  form  from  the  object,  as 
does  every  act.  If  therefore  man  is  bound  to  conform  his 
will  to  the  Divine  will,  it  follows  that  he  is  bound  to  conform 
it,  as  to  the  thing  willed. 

(3)  Moreover,  opposition  of  wills  arises  from  men  willing 
different  things.  But  whoever  has  a  will  in  opposition  to 
the  Divine  will,  has  an  evil  will.  Therefore  whoever  does 
not  conform  his  will  to  the  Divine  will,  as  to  the  thing 
willed,  has  an  evil  will. 

/  answer  that,  As  is  evident  from  what  has  been  said  above 
(AA.  3,  5),  the  will  tends  to  its  object,  according  as  it  is 
proposed  by  the  reason.  Now  a  thing  may  be  considered 
in  various  ways  by  the  reason,  so  as  to  appear  good  from 
one  point  of  view,  and  not  good  from  another  point  of  view. 
And  therefore  if  a  man's  will  wills  a  thing  to  be,  according 
as  it  appears  to  be  good,  his  will  is  good:  and  the  will  of 
another  man,  who  wills  that  thing  not  to  be,  according  as  it 
appears  evil,  is  also  good.  Thus  a  judge  has  a  good  will,  in 
willing  a  thief  to  be  put  to  death,  because  this  is  just:  while 
the  will  of  another — e.g.,  the  thief's  wife  or  son,  who  wishes 
him  not  to  be  put  to  death,  inasmuch  as  killing  is  a  natural 
evil,  is  also  good. 

Now  since  the  will  follows  the  apprehension  of  the  reason 
or  intellect;  the  more  universal  the  aspect  of  the  appre- 
hended good,  the  more  universal  the  good  to  which  the 
will  tends.  This  is  evident  in  the  example  given  above: 
because  the  judge  has  care  of  the  common  good,  which  is 
justice,  and  therefore  he  wishes  the  thief's  death,  which 
has  the  aspect  of  good  in  relation  to  the  common  estate; 
whereas  the  thief's  wife  has  to  consider  the  private  good 
of  the  family,  and  from  this  point  of  view  she  wishes  her 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  253 

husband,  the  thief,  not  to  be  put  to  death. — Now  the  good 
of  the  whole  universe  is  that  which  is  apprehended  by  God, 
Who  is  the  Maker  and  Governor  of  all  things:  hence  what- 
ever He  wills,  He  wills  it  under  the  aspect  of  the  common 
good;  this  is  His  own  Goodness,  which  is  the  good  of  the 
whole  universe.  On  the  other  hand,  the  apprehension  of  a 
creature,  according  to  its  nature,  is  of  some  particular  good, 
proportionate  to  that  nature.  Now  a  thing  may  happen 
to  be  good  under  a  particular  aspect,  and  yet  not  good 
under  a  universal  aspect,  or  vice  versa,  as  stated  above. 
And  therefore  it  comes  to  pass  that  a  certain  will  is  good 
from  willing  something  considered  under  a  particular  aspect, 
which  thing  God  wills  not,  under  a  universal  aspect,  and 
vice  versa.  And  hence  too  it  is  that  various  wills  of 
various  men  can  be  good  in  respect  of  opposite  things,  for 
as  much  as,  under  various  aspects,  they  wish  a  particular 
thing  to  be  or  not  to  be. 

But  a  man's  will  is  not  right  in  willing  a  particular  good, 
unless  he  refer  it  to  the  common  good  as  an  end:  since  even 
the  natural  appetite  of  each  part  is  ordained  to  the  common 
good  of  the  whole.  Now  it  is  the  end  that  supplies  the 
formal  reason,  as  it  were,  of  willing  whatever  is  directed  to 
the  end.  Consequently,  in  order  that  a  man  will  some 
particular  good  with  a  right  will,  he  must  will  that  par- 
ticular good  materially,  and  the  Divine  and  universal  good, 
formally.  Therefore  the  human  will  is  bound  to  be  con- 
formed to  the  Divine  will,  as  to  that  which  is  willed  formally, 
for  it  is  bound  to  will  the  Divine  and  universal  good;  but 
not  as  to  that  which  is  willed  materially,  for  the  reason 
given  above. 

At  the  same  time  in  both  these  respects,  the  human  will 
is  conformed  to  the  Divine,  in  a  certain  degree.  Because 
inasmuch  as  it  is  conformed  to  the  Divine  will  in  the  com- 
mon aspect  of  the  thing  willed,  it  is  conformed  thereto  in 
the  point  of  the  last  end.  While,  inasmuch  as  it  is  not 
conformed  to  the  Divine  will  in  the  thing  willed  materially, 
it  is  conformed  to  that  will  considered  as  efficient  cause; 
since  the  proper  inclination  consequent  to   nature,   or  to 


254  QUESTION  XIX 

the  particular  apprehension  of  some  particular  thing,  comes 
to  a  thing  from  God  as  its  efficient  cause.  Hence  it  is 
customary  to  say  that  a  man's  will,  in  this  respect,  is  con- 
formed to  the  Divine  will,  because  it  wills  what  God  wishes 
him  to  will. 

There  is  yet  another  kind  of  conformity  in  respect  of  the 
formal  cause,  consisting  in  man's  willing  something  from 
charity,  as  God  wills  it.  And  this  conformity  is  also  reduced 
to  the  formal  conformity,  that  is  in  respect  of  the  last  end, 
which  is  the  proper  object  of  charity. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  We  can  know  in  a  general  way  what  God 
wills.  For  we  know  that  whatever  God  wills,  He  wills  it 
under  the  aspect  of  good.  Consequently  whoever  wills  a 
thing  under  any  aspect  of  good,  has  a  will  conformed  to  the 
Divine  will,  as  to  the  reason  of  the  thing  willed.  But  we 
know  not  what  God  wills  in  particular:  and  in  this  respect 
we  are  not  bound  to  conform  our  will  to  the  Divine  will. 

But  in  the  state  of  glory,  every  one  will  see  in  each  thing 
that  he  wills,  the  relation  of  that  thing  to  what  God  wills  in 
that  particular  matter.  Consequently  they  will  conform 
their  will  to  God  in  all  things  not  only  formally,  but  also 
materially. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  God  does  not  will  the  damnation  of  a  man, 
considered  precisely  as  damnation,  nor  a  man's  death, 
considered  precisely  as  death,  because,  He  wills  all  men  to 
be  saved  (i  Tim.  ii.  4) :  but  He  wills  such  things  under  the 
aspect  of  justice.  Wherefore  in  regard  to  such  things  it 
suffices  for  man  to  will  the  upholding  of  God's  justice  and 
of  the  natural  order. 

Wherefore  the  reply  to  the  Third  Objection  is  evident. 

To  the  first  argument  advanced  in  a  contrary  sense,  it 
should  be  said  that  a  man  who  conforms  his  will  to  God's, 
in  the  aspect  of  reason  of  the  thing  willed,  wills  what  God 
wills,  more  than  the  man,  who  conforms  his  will  to  God's, 
in  the  point  of  the  very  thing  willed ;  because  the  will  tends 
more  to  the  end,  than  to  that  which  is  on  account  of  the 
end. 

To  the  second,  it  must  be  replied  that  the  species  and  form 


GOODNESS  OF  THE  WILL  255 

of  an  act  are  taken  from  the  object  considered  formally, 
rather  than  from  the  object  considered  materially. 

To  the  third,  it  must  be  said  that  there  is  no  opposition 
of  wills  when  several  people  desire  different  things,  but 
not  under  the  same  aspect :  but  there  is  opposition  of  wills, 
when  under  one  and  the  same  aspect,  one  man  wills  a  thing 
which  another  wills  not.  But  there  is  no  question  of  this 
here. 


QUESTION  XX 

OF  GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  IN  EXTERNAL  HUMAN 

ACTIONS. 

[In  Six  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  goodness  and  malice  as  to  external 
actions:  under  which  point  there  are  six  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  goodness  and  malice  is  first  in  the  act  of  the 
will,  or  in  the  external  action  ?  (2)  Whether  the  whole 
goodness  or  malice  of  the  external  action  depends  on  the 
goodness  of  the  will  ?  (3)  Whether  the  goodness  and  malice 
of  the  interior  act  are  the  same  as  those  of  the  external 
action  ?  (4)  Whether  the  external  action  adds  any  good- 
ness or  malice  to  that  of  the  interior  act  ?  (5)  Whether  the 
consequences  of  an  external  action  increase  its  goodness  or 
malice  ?  (6)  Whether  one  and  the  same  external  action  can 
be  both  good  and  evil  ? 

First  Article, 

whether  goodness  or  malice  is  first  in  the  act  of  the 
will.  or  in  the  external  action  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  good  and  evil  are  in  the  external 
action  prior  to  being  in  the  act  of  the  will.  For  the  will 
derives  goodness  from  its  object,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XIX., 
AA.  I,  2).  But  the  externa]  action  is  the  object  of  the 
interior  act  of  the  will:  for  a  man  is  said  to  will  to  commit 
a  theft,  or  to  will  to  give  an  alms.  Therefore  good  and  evil 
are  in  the  external  action,  prior  to  being  in  the  act  of  the 

will. 

256 


GOODNESS  OF  EXTERNAL  ACTION  257 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  aspect  of  good  belongs  first  to  the 
end :  since  what  is  directed  to  the  end  receives  the  aspect  of 
good  from  its  relation  to  the  end.  Now  whereas  the  act  of 
the  will  cannot  be  an  end,  as  stated  above  (Q.  I.,  A.  i  ad  2), 
the  act  of  another  power  can  be  an  end.  Therefore  good 
is  in  the  act  of  some  other  power  prior  to  being  in  the  act  of 
the  will. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  act  of  the  will  stands  in  a  formal 
relation  to  the  external  action,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XVIII. , 
A.  6).  But  that  which  is  formal  is  subsequent;  since  form 
is  something  added  to  matter.  Therefore  good  and  evil  are 
in  the  external  action,  prior  to  being  in  the  act  of  the  will. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {Retract,  i.)  that  it  is  by 
the  will  that  we  sin,  and  that  we  behave  aright.  Therefore 
moral  good  and  evil  are  first  in  the  will. 

/  answer  that.  External  actions  may  be  said  to  be  good  or 
bad  in  two  ways.  First,  in  regard  to  their  genus,  and  the 
circumstances  connected  with  them :  thus  the  giving  of  alms, 
if  the  required  conditions  be  observed,  is  said  to  be  good. 
Secondly,  a  thing  is  said  to  be  good  or  evil,  from  its  relation 
to  the  end :  thus  the  giving  of  alms  for  vainglory,  is  said  to 
be  evil.  Now,  since  the  end  is  the  will's  proper  object,  it 
is  evident  that  this  aspect  of  good  or  evil,  which  the  external 
action  derives  from  its  relation  to  the  end,  is  to  be  found 
first  of  all  in  the  act  of  the  will,  whence  it  passes  to  the 
external  action.  On  the  other  hand,  the  goodness  or  malice 
which  the  external  action  has  of  itself,  on  account  of  its 
being  about  due  matter  and  its  being  attended  by  due  cir- 
cumstances, is  not  derived  from  the  will,  but  rather  from 
the  reason.  Consequently,  if  we  consider  the  goodness  of 
the  external  action,  in  so  far  as  it  comes  from  reason's 
ordination  and  apprehension,  it  is  prior  to  the  goodness  of 
the  act  of  the  will :  but  if  we  consider  it  in  so  far  as  it  is  in 
the  execution  of  the  action  done,  it  is  subsequent  to  the 
goodness  of  the  will,  which  is  its  principle. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  exterior  action  is  the  object  of  the  will, 
inasmuch  as  it  is  proposed  to  the  will  by  the  reason,  as  a 
good  apprehended  and  ordained  by  the  reason:  and  thus  it 

II.  I  17 


258  QUESTION  XX 

is  prior  to  the  good  in  the  act  of  the  will.  But  inasmuch  as 
it  is  found  in  the  execution  of  the  action,  it  is  an  effect  of  the 
will,  and  is  subsequent  to  the  will. 

Reply  Ob].  2.  The  end  precedes  in  the  order  of  intention, 
but  follows  in  the  order  of  execution. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  A  form  as  received  into  matter,  is  subsequent 
to  matter  in  the  order  of  generation,  although  it  precedes 
it  in  the  order  of  nature :  but  inasmuch  as  it  is  in  the  active 
cause,  it  precedes  in  every  way.  Now  the  will  is  compared 
to  the  exterior  action,  as  its  efficient  cause.  Wherefore  the 
goodness  of  the  act  of  the  will,  as  existing  in  the  active 
cause,  is  the  form  of  the  exterior  action. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  whole  goodness  and  malice  of  the  exter- 
nal action  depend  on  the  goodness  of  the  will  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — - 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  whole  goodness  and  malice 
of  the  external  action  depend  on  the  goodness  of  the  will. 
For  it  is  written  (Matth.  vii.  18):  A  good  tree  cannot  bring 
forth  evil  fruit,  neither  can  an  evil  tree  bring  forth  good  fruit. 
But,  according  to  the  gloss,  the  tree  signifies  the  will,  and 
fruit  signifies  works.  Therefore  it  is  impossible  for  the 
interior  act  of  the  will  to  be  good,  and  the  external  action 
evil,  or  vice  versa. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Augustine  says  (Retract,  i.)  that  there  is 
no  sin  without  the  will.  If  therefore  there  is  no  sin  in  the 
will,  there  will  be  none  in  the  external  action.  And  so  the 
whole  goodness  or  malice  of  the  external  action  depends 
on  the  will. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  good  and  evil  of  which  we  are  speak- 
ing now  are  differences  of  the  moral  act.  Now  differences 
make  an  essential  division  in  a  genus,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  (Metaph.  vii.).  Since  therefore  an  act  is  moral 
from  being  voluntary,  it  seems  that  goodness  and  malice  in 
an  act  are  derived  from  the  will  alone. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Contra  Mendac.  vii.), 


GOODNESS  OF  EXTERNAL  ACTION  259 

that  there  are  some  actions  which  neither  a  good  end  nor  a  good 
will  can  make  good, 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  we  may  consider  a 
twofold  goodness  or  malice  in  the  external  action:  one  in 
respect  of  due  matter  and  circumstances;  the  other  in 
respect  of  the  order  to  the  end.  And  that  which  is  in  respect 
of  the  order  to  the  end,  depends  entirely  on  the  will :  while 
that  which  is  in  respect  of  due  matter  or  circumstances, 
depends  on  the  reason:  and  on  this  goodness  depends  the 
goodness  of  the  will,  in  so  far  as  the  will  tends  towards  it. 

Now  it  must  be  observed,  as  was  noted  above  (Q.  XIX., 
A.  6  ad  i),  that  for  a  thing  to  be  evil,  one  single  defect 
suffices,  whereas,  for  it  to  be  good  simply,  it  is  not  enough 
for  it  to  be  good  in  one  point  only,  it  must  be  good  in  every 
respect.  If  therefore  the  will  be  good,  both  from  its  proper 
object  and  from  its  end,  it  follows  that  the  external  action 
is  good.  But  if  the  will  be  good  from  its  intention  of  the 
end,  this  is  not  enough  to  make  the  external  action  good: 
and  if  the  will  be  evil  either  by  reason  of  its  intention  of 
the  end,  or  by  reason  of  the  act  willed,  it  follows  that  the 
external  action  is  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  If  the  good  tree  be  taken  to  signify  the 
good  will,  it  must  be  in  so  far  as  the  will  derives  goodness 
from  the  act  willed  and  from  the  end  intended. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  man  sins  by  his  will,  not  only  when  he 
wills  an  evil  end;  but  also  when  he  wills  an  evil  act. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Voluntariness  applies  not  only  to  the  interior 
act  of  the  will,  but  also  to  external  actions,  inasmuch  as  they 
proceed  from  the  will  and  the  reason.  Consequently  the 
difference  of  good  and  evil  is  applicable  to  both  the  interior 
and  external  act. 

Third  Article. 

whether  the  goodness  and  malice  of  the  external 
action  are  the  same  as  those  of  the  interior  act  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — - 
Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  the  goodness  and  malice  of 
the  interior  act  of  the  will  are  not  the  same  as  those  of  the 


26o  QUESTION  XX 

external  action.  For  the  principle  of  the  interior  act  is  the 
interior  apprehensive  or  appetitive  power  of  the  soul; 
whereas  the  principle  of  the  external  action  is  the  power 
that  accomplishes  the  movement.  Now  where  the  princi- 
ples of  action  are  different,  the  actions  themselves  are  dif- 
ferent. Moreover,  it  is  the  action  which  is  the  subject  of 
goodness  or  malice:  and  the  same  accident  cannot  be  in 
different  subjects.  Therefore  the  goodness  of  the  interior 
act  cannot  be  the  same  as  that  of  the  external  action. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  A  virtue  makes  that,  which  has  it,  good, 
and  renders  its  action  good  also  (Ethic,  ii.).  But  the  intel- 
lectual virtue  in  the  commanding  power  is  distinct  from 
the  moral  virtue  in  the  power  commanded,  as  is  declared 
in  Ethic,  i.  Therefore  the  goodness  of  the  interior  act, 
which  belongs  to  the  commanding  power,  is  distinct  from 
the  goodness  of  the  external  action,  which  belongs  to  the 
power  commanded. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  same  thing  cannot  be  cause  and 
effect;  since  nothing  is  its  own  cause.  But  the  goodness 
of  the  interior  act  is  the  cause  of  the  goodness  of  the  ex- 
ternal action,  or  vice  versa,  as  stated  above  (AA.  i,  2). 
Therefore  it  is  not  the  same  goodness  in  each. 

On  the  contrary,  It  was  shown  above  (Q.  XVIII.,  A.  6) 
that  the  act  of  the  will  is  the  form,  as  it  were,  of  the  external 
action.  Now  that  which  results  from  the  material  and 
formal  element  is  one  thing.  Therefore  there  is  but  one 
goodness  of  the  internal  and  external  act. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XVII.,  A.  4),  the  in- 
terior act  of  the  will,  and  the  external  action,  considered 
morally,  are  one  act.  Now  it  happens  sometimes  that  one 
and  the  same  individual  act  has  several  aspects  of  goodness 
or  malice,  and  sometimes  that  it  has  but  one.  Hence  we 
must  say  that  sometimes  the  goodness  of  the  interior  act  is 
the  same  as  that  of  the  external  action,  and  sometimes  not. 
For  as  we  have  already  said  (AA.  1,2),  these  two  goodnesses 
or  malices,  of  the  internal  and  external  acts,  are  ordained 
to  one  another.  Now  it  may  happen,  in  things  that  are 
subordinate  to  something  else,  that  a  thing  is  good  merely 


GOODNESS  OF  EXTERNAL  ACTION  261 

from  being  subordinate;  thus  a  bitter  draught,  is  good 
merely  because  it  procures  health.  Wherefore  there  are  not 
two  goodnesses,  one  the  goodness  of  health,  and  the  other 
the  goodness  of  the  draught;  but  one  and  the  same.  On 
the  other  hand  it  happens  sometimes  that  that  which  is 
subordinate  to  another,  has  some  aspect  of  goodness  in 
itself,  besides  the  fact  of  its  being  subordinate  to  some  other 
good:  thus  a  palatable  medicine  can  be  considered  in  the 
light  of  a  pleasurable  good,  besides  of  being  conducive  to 
health. 

We  must  therefore  say  that  when  the  external  action 
derives  goodness  or  malice  from  its  relation  to  the  end  only, 
then  there  is  but  one  and  the  same  goodness  of  the  act  of 
the  will  which  of  itself  regards  the  end,  and  of  the  external 
action,  which  regards  the  end  through  the  medium  of  the 
act  of  the  will.  But  when  the  external  action  has  goodness 
or  malice  of  itself,  i.e.,  in  regard  to  its  matter  and  circum- 
stances, then  the  goodness  of  the  external  action  is  distinct 
from  the  goodness  of  the  will  in  regarding  the  end:  yet  so 
that  the  goodness  of  the  end  passes  into  the  external  action, 
and  the  goodness  of  the  matter  and  circumstances  passes 
into  the  act  of  the  will,  as  stated  above  (AA.  i,  2). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  argument  proves  that  the  internal  and 
external  actions  are  different  in  the  physical  order:  yet 
distinct  as  they  are  in  that  respect,  they  combine  to  form 
one  thing  in  the  moral  order,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XVIL, 
A.  4). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  As  stated  in  Ethic,  vi.,  a  moral  virtue  is 
ordained  to  the  act  of  that  virtue,  which  act  is  the  end, 
as  it  were,  of  that  virtue;  whereas  prudence,  which  is  in 
the  reason,  is  ordained  to  things  directed  to  the  end.  For 
this  reason  various  virtues  are  necessary.  But  right  reason 
in  regard  to  the  very  end  of  a  virtue  has  no  other  goodness 
than  the  goodness  of  that  virtue,  in  so  far  as  the  goodness 
of  the  reason  is  participated  in  each  virtue. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  When  a  thing  is  derived  by  one  thing  from 
another,  as  from  a  uni vocal  efficient  cause,  then  it  is  not 
the  same  in  both:  thus  when  a  hot  thing  heats,  the  heat  of 


262  QUESTION  XX 

the  heater  is  distinct  from  the  heat  of  the  thing  heated, 
although  it  be  the  same  specifically.  But  when  a  thing  is 
derived  by  one  thing  from  another,  according  to  analogy 
or  proportion,  then  it  is  one  and  the  same  in  both:  thus 
the  healthiness  which  is  in  medicine  or  urine  is  derived  from 
the  healthiness  of  the  animal's  body ;  nor  is  health  as  applied 
to  urine  and  medicine,  distinct  from  health  as  applied  to 
the  body  of  an  animal,  of  which  health  medicine  is  the  cause, 
and  urine  the  sign.  It  is  in  this  way  that  the  goodness  of 
the  external  action  is  derived  from  the  goodness  of  the  will, 
and  vice  versa;  viz.,  according  to  the  order  of  one  to  the 
other. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  external  action  adds  any  goodness  or 
malice  to  that  of  the  interior  act  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  external  action  does  not 
add  any  goodness  or  malice  to  that  of  the  interior  action. 
For  Chrysostom  says  {Horn.  xix.  in  Matth.) :  It  is  the  will 
that  is  rewarded  for  doing  good,  or  punished  jor  doing  evil. 
Now  works  are  the  witnesses  of  the  will.  Therefore  God  seeks 
for  works  not  on  His  own  account,  in  order  to  know  how  to 
judge;  but  for  the  sake  of  others,  that  all  may  understand 
how  just  He  is.  But  good  or  evil  is  to  be  estimated  according 
to  God's  judgment  rather  than  according  to  the  judgment 
of  man.  Therefore  the  external  action  adds  no  goodness 
or  malice  to  that  of  the  interior  act. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  goodness  and  malice  of  the  interior 
and  external  acts  are  one  and  the  same,  as  stated  above 
(A.  3).  But  increase  is  the  addition  of  one  thing  to  another. 
Therefore  the  external  action  does  not  add  to  the  goodness 
01'  malice  of  the  interior  act. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  entire  goodness  of  created  things 
does  not  add  to  the  Divine  Goodness,  because  it  is  entirely 
derived  therefrom.  But  sometimes  the  entire  goodness  of 
the  external  action  is  derived  from  the  goodness  of  the 
interior  act,   and  sometimes   conversely,   as  stated   above 


GOODNESS  OF  EXTERNAL  ACTION  263 

(AA.  I,  2).  Therefore  neither  of  them  adds  to  the  goodness 
or  malice  of  the  other. 

On  the  contrary,  Every  agent  intends  to  attain  good  and 
avoid  evil.  If  therefore  by  the  external  action  no  further 
goodness  or  malice  be  added,  it  is  to  no  purpose  that  he  who 
has  a  good  or  an  evil  will,  does  a  good  deed  or  refrains  from 
an  evil  deed.     Which  is  unreasonable. 

/  answer  that,  If  we  speak  of  the  goodness  which  the 
external  action  derives  from  the  will  tending  to  the  end, 
then  the  external  action  adds  nothing  to  this  goodness, 
unless  it  happen  that  the  will  in  itself  is  made  better  in  good 
things,  or  worse  in  evil  things.  This,  seemingly,  may  happen 
in  three  ways.  First  in  point  of  number;  if,  for  instance,  a 
man  wishes  to  do  something  with  a  good  or  an  evil  end  in 
view,  and  does  not  do  it  then,  but  afterwards  wills  and  does 
it,  the  act  of  his  will  is  doubled,  and  a  double  good,  or  a 
double  evil  is  the  result. — Secondly,  in  point  of  extension: 
when,  for  instance,  a  man  wishes  to  do  something  for  a  good 
or  an  evil  end,  and  is  hindered  by  some  obstacle,  whereas 
another  man  perseveres  in  the  movement  of  the  will  until 
he  accomplish  it  in  deed ;  it  is  evident  that  the  will  of  the 
latter  is  more  lasting  in  good  or  evil,  and,  in  this  respect, 
is  better  or  worse. — Thirdly,  in  point  of  intensity:  for  there 
are  certain  external  actions,  which,  in  so  far  as  they  are 
pleasurable  or  painful,  are  such  as  naturally  to  make  the 
will  more  intense  or  more  remiss;  and  it  is  evident  that 
the  more  intensely  the  will  tends  to  good  or  evil,  the  better 
or  worse  it  is. 

On  the  other  hand,  if  we  speak  of  the  goodness  which 
the  external  action  derives  from  its  matter  and  due  cir- 
cumstances, thus  it  stands  in  relation  to  the  will  as  its  term 
and  end.  And  in  this  way  it  adds  to  the  goodness  or  malice 
of  the  will;  because  every  inclination  or  movement  is  per- 
fected by  attaining  its  end  or  reaching  its  term.  Wherefore 
the  will  is  not  perfect,  unless  it  be  such  that,  given  the  oppor- 
tunity, it  reahzes  the  operation.  But  if  this  prove  impossible, 
as  long  as  the  will  is  perfect,  so  as  to  realize  the  operation 
if  it  could;  the  lack  of  perfection  derived  from  the  external 


264  QUESTION  XX 

action,  is  simply  involuntary.  Now  just  as  the  involuntary 
deserves  neither  punishment  nor  reward  in  the  accomplish- 
ment of  good  or  evil  deeds,  so  neither  does  it  lessen  reward 
or  punishment,  if  a  man  through  simple  in  voluntariness 
fail  to  do  good  or  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Chrysostom  is  speaking  of  the  case  where 
a  man's  will  is  complete,  and  does  not  refrain  from  the  deed 
save  through  the  impossibility  of  achievement. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  This  argument  applies  to  that  goodness 
which  the  external  action  derives  from  the  will  as  tending  to 
the  end.  But  the  goodness  which  the  external  action 
takes  from  its  matter  and  circumstances,  is  distinct  from 
that  which  it  derives  from  the  end;  but  it  is  not  distinct 
from  that  which  it  has  from  the  very  act  willed,  to  which  it 
stands  in  the  relation  of  measure  and  cause,  as  stated  above 
(AA.  I,  2.) 

From  this  the  reply  to  the  Third  Objection  is  evident. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  the  consequences  of  the  external  action 
increase  its  goodness  or  malice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Ai'ticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  consequences  of  the  external 
action  increase  its  goodness  or  malice.  For  the  effect  pre- 
exists virtually  in  its  cause.  But  the  consequences  result 
from  the  action  as  an  effect  from  its  cause.  Therefore  they 
pre-exist  virtually  in  actions.  Now  a  thing  is  judged  to  be 
good  or  bad  according  to  its  virtue,  since  a  virtue  makes 
that  which  has  it  to  be  good  (Ethic,  ii.).  Therefore  the  con- 
sequences increase  the  goodness  or  malice  of  an  action. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  good  actions  of  his  hearers  are  conse- 
quences resulting  from  the  words  of  a  preacher.  But  such 
goods  as  these  redound  to  the  merit  of  the  preacher,  as  is 
evident  from  Phil.  iv.  i:  My  dearly  beloved  brethren,  my 
joy  and  my  crown.  Therefore  the  consequences  of  an  action 
increase  its  goodness  or  malice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Punishment  is  not  increased,  unless  the 


GOODNESS  OF  EXTERNAL  ACTION  265 

fault  increases:  wherefore  it  is  written  (Deut.  xxv.  2): 
According  to  the  measure  of  the  sin  shall  the  measure  also 
of  the  stripes  he.  But  the  punishment  is  increased  on 
account  of  the  consequences ;  for  it  is  written  (Exod.  xxi.  29) : 
But  if  the  ox  was  wont  to  push  with  his  horn  yesterday  and 
the  day  before,  and  they  warned  his  master,  and  he  did  not 
shut  him  up,  and  he  shall  kill  a  man  or  a  woman,  then  the 
ox  shall  be  stoned,  and  his  owner  also  shall  be  put  to  death. 
But  he  would  not  have  been  put  to  death,  if  the  ox,  although 
he  had  not  been  shut  up,  had  not  killed  a  man.  Therefore 
the  consequences  increase  the  goodness  or  malice  of  an  action. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  if  a  man  do  something  which  may  cause 
death,  by  striking,  or  by  sentencing,  and  if  death  does  not 
ensue,  he  does  not  contract  irregularity:  but  he  would  if 
death  were  to  ensue.  Therefore  the  consequences  of  an 
action  increase  its  goodness  or  malice. 

On  the  contrary,  The  consequences  do  not  make  an  action 
that  was  evil,  to  be  good;  nor  one  that  was  good,  to  be  evil. 
For  instance,  if  a  man  give  an  alms  to  a  poor  man  who 
makes  bad  use  of  the  alms  by  committing  a  sin,  this  does 
not  undo  the  good  done  by  the  giver;  and,  in  like  manner, 
if  a  man  bear  patiently  a  wrong  done  to  him,  the  wrong- 
doer is  not  thereby  excused.  Therefore  the  consequences 
of  an  action  do  not  increase  its  goodness  or  malice. 

/  answer  that,  The  consequences  of  an  action  are  either 
foreseen  or  not.  If  they  are  foreseen,  it  is  evident  that  they 
increase  the  goodness  or  malice.  For  when  a  man  foresees 
that  many  evils  may  follow  from  his  action,  and  yet  does 
not  therefore  desist  therefrom,  this  shows  his  will  to  be  all 
the  more  inordinate. 

But  if  the  consequences  are  not  foreseen,  we  must  make 
a  distinction.  Because  if  they  follow  from  the  nature  of 
the  action,  and  in  the  majority  of  cases,  in  this  respect, 
the  consequences  increase  the  goodness  or  malice  of  that 
action :  for  it  is  evident  that  an  action  is  specifically  better, 
if  better  results  can  follow  from  it;  and  specifically  worse, 
if  it  is  of  a  nature  to  produce  worse  results. — On  the  other 
hand,  if  the  consequences  follow  by  accident  and  seldom, 


266  QUESTION  XX 

then  they  do  not  increase  the  goodness  or  malice  of  the  action : 
because  we  do  not  judge  of  a  thing  according  to  that  which 
belongs  to  it  by  accident,  but  only  according  to  that  which 
belongs  to  it  of  itself. 

Re  fly  Ohj.  i.  The  virtue  of  a  cause  is  measured  by  the 
effect  that  flows  from  the  nature  of  the  cause,  not  by  that 
which  results  by  accident. 

Rej)ly  Ohj.  2.  The  good  actions  done  by  the  hearers, 
result  from  the  preacher's  words,  as  an  effect  that  flows 
from  their  very  nature.  Hence  they  redound  to  the  merit 
of  the  preacher :  especially  when  such  is  his  intention. 

Rej)ly  Ohj.  3.  The  consequences  for  which  that  man  is 
ordered  to  be  punished,  both  follow  from  the  nature  of  the 
cause,  and  are  supposed  to  be  foreseen.  For  this  reason 
they  are  reckoned  as  punishable. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  This  argument  would  prove  if  irregularity 
were  the  result  of  the  fault.  But  it  is  not  the  result  of  the 
fault,  but  of  the  fact,  and  of  the  obstacle  to  the  reception 
of  a  sacrament. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  one  and  the  same  external  action  can  be 
both  good  and  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  one  and  the  same  external 
action  can  be  both  good  and  evil.  For  movement,  if  con- 
tinuous, is  one  and  the  same  [Phys.  v.).  But  one  continuous 
movement  can  be  both  good  and  bad:  for  instance,  a  man 
may  go  to  Church  continuously,  intending  at  first  vainglory, 
and  afterwards  the  service  of  God.  Therefore  one  and  the 
same  action  can  be  both  good  and  evil. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  according  to  the  Philosopher  {Phys.  iii.), 
action  and  passion  are  one  act.  But  the  passion  may  be 
good,  as  Christ's  was;  and  the  action  evil,  as  that  of  the 
Jews.  Therefore  one  and  the  same  act  can  be  both  good 
and  evil. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  since  a  servant  is  an  instrument,  as  it 
were,  of  his  master,  the  servant's  action  is  his  master's,  just 


GOODNESS  OF  EXTERNAL  ACITON  267 

as  the  action  of  a  tool  is  the  workman's  action.  But  it  may 
happen  that  the  servant's  action  result  from  his  master's 
good  will,  and  is  therefore  good:  and  from  the  evil  will  of 
the  servant,  and  is  therefore  evil.  Therefore  the  same 
action  can  be  both  good  and  evil. 

On  the  contrary,  The  same  thing  cannot  be  the  subject 
of  contraries.  But  good  and  evil  are  contraries.  There- 
fore the  same  action  cannot  be  both  good  and  evil. 

/  answer  that,  Nothing  hinders  a  thing  from  being  one, 
in  so  far  as  it  is  in  one  genus,  and  manifold,  in  so  far  as  it 
is  referred  to  another  genus.  Thus  a  continuous  surface 
is  one,  considered  as  in  the  genus  of  quantity;  and  yet  it  is 
manifold,  considered  as  to  the  genus  of  colour,  if  it  be 
partly  white,  and  partly  black.  And  accordingly,  nothing 
hinders  an  action  from  being  one,  considered  in  the  natural 
order ;  whereas  it  is  not  one,  considered  in  the  moral  order ; 
and  vice  versa,  as  we  have  stated  above  (A.  3  i?^  i ;  Q.  XVIIL, 
A.  y  adi).  P'or  continuous  walking  is  one  action,  considered 
in  the  natural  order:  but  it  may  resolve  itself  into  many 
actions,  considered  in  the  moral  order  if  a  change  take 
place  in  the  walker's  will,  for  the  will  is  the  principle  of 
moral  actions.  If  therefore  we  consider  an  action  in  the 
moral  order,  it  is  impossible  for  it  to  be  morally  both  good 
and  evil.  Whereas  if  it  be  one  as  to  natural  and  not  moral 
unity,  it  can  be  both  good  and  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  continual  movement  which  proceeds 
from  various  intentions,  although  it  is  one  in  the  natural 
order,  is  not  one  in  the  point  of  moral  unity. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Action  and  passion  belong  to  the  moral 
order,  in  so  far  as  they  are  voluntary.  And  therefore  in  so 
far  as  they  are  voluntary  in  respect  of  wills  that  differ,  they 
are  two  distinct  things,  and  good  can  be  in  one  of  them, 
while  evil  is  in  the  other. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  action  of  the  servant,  in  so  far  as  it 
proceeds  from  the  will  of  the  servant,  is  not  the  master's 
action:  but  only  in  so  far  as  it  proceeds  from  the  master's 
command.  Wherefore  the  evil  will  of  the  servant  does  not 
make  the  action  evil  in  this  respect. 


QUESTION  XXI. 

OF  THE  CONSEQUENCES  OF  HUMAN  ACTIONS  BY  REASON 
OF  THEIR  GOODNESS  AND  MALICE. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  have  now  to  consider  the  consequences  of  human  actions 
by  reason  of  their  goodness  and  malice :  and  under  this  head 
there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  a  human 
action  is  right  or  sinful,  by  reason  of  its  being  good  or 
evil  ?     (2)  Whether  it  thereby  deserves  praise  or  blame  ? 

(3)  Whether  accordingly,  it  is  meritorious  or  demeritorious  ? 

(4)  Whether  it  is  accordingly  meritorious  or  demeritorious 
before  God  ? 

First  x\rticle. 
whether  a  human  action  is  right  or  sinful,  in  so  far 
as  it  is  good  or  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  a  human  action  is  not  right 
or  sinful,  in  so  far  as  it  is  good  or  evil.  For  monsters  are  the 
sins  of  nature  {Phys.  ii.).  But  monsters  are  not  actions, 
but  things  engendered  outside  the  order  of  nature.  Now 
things  that  are  produced  according  to  art  and  reason  imitate 
those  that  are  produced  according  to  nature  (ibid.).  There- 
fore an  action  is  not  sinful  by  reason  of  its  being  inordinate 
and  evil. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  sin,  as  stated  in  Phys.  ii.,  occurs  in  nature 
and  art,  when  the  end  intended  by  nature  or  art  is  not 
attained.  But  the  goodness  or  malice  of  a  human  action 
depends,  before  all,  on  the  intention  of  the  end,  and  on  its 
achievement.  Therefore  it  seems  that  the  malice  of  an 
action  does  not  make  it  sinful. 

268 


ACTIONS  RIGHT  OR  SINFUL  269 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  the  malice  of  an  action  makes  it  sinful, 
it  follows  that  wherever  there  is  evil,  there  is  sin.  But  this 
is  false:  since  punishment  is  not  a  sin,  although  it  is  an  evil. 
Therefore  an  action  is  not  sinful  by  reason  of  its  being  evil. 

On  the  contrary,  As  shown  above,  the  goodness  of  a  human 
action  depends  principally  on  the  Eternal  Law:  and  conse- 
quently its  malice  consists  in  its  being  in  disaccord  with 
the  Eternal  Law.  But  this  is  the  very  nature  of  sin;  for 
Augustine  says  {Contra  Faust,  xxii.)  that  sin  is  a  word, 
deed,  or  desire,  in  opposition  to  the  Eternal  Law.  Therefore 
a  human  action  is  sinful  by  reason  of  its  being  evil. 

/  answer  that,  Evil  is  more  comprehensive  than  sin,  as 
also  is  good  than  right.  For  every  privation  of  good,  in 
whatever  subject,  is  an  evil:  whereas  sin  consists  properly 
in  an  action  done  for  a  certain  end,  and  lacking  due  order 
to  that  end.  Now  the  due  order  to  an  end  is  measured 
by  some  rule.  In  things  that  act  according  to  nature,  this 
rule  is  the  natural  force  that  inclines  them  to  that  end. 
When  therefore  an  action  proceeds  from  a  natural  force, 
in  accord  with  the  natural  inclination  to  an  end,  then  the 
action  is  said  to  be  right :  since  the  mean  does  not  exceed  its 
limits,  viz.,  the  action  does  not  swerve  from  the  order  of 
its  active  principle  to  the  end.  But  when  an  action  strays 
from  this  rectitude,  it  comes  under  the  notion  of  sin. 

Now  in  those  things  that  are  done  by  the  will,  the  proxi- 
mate rule  is  the  human  reason,  while  the  supreme  rule  is 
the  Eternal  Law.  When,  therefore,  a  human  action  tends 
to  the  end,  according  to  the  order  of  reason  and  of  the 
Eternal  Law,  then  that  action  is  right:  but  when  it  turns 
aside  from  that  rectitude,  then  it  is  said  to  be  a  sin.  Now 
it  is  evident  from  what  has  been  said  (Q.  XIX.,  AA.  3,  4) 
that  every  voluntary  action  that  turns  aside  from  the  order 
of  reason  and  of  the  Eternal  Law,  is  evil,  and  that  every 
good  action  is  in  accord  with  reason  and  the  Eternal  Law. 
Hence  it  follows  that  a  human  action  is  right  or  sinful  by 
reason  of  its  being  good  or  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Monsters  are  called  sins,  inasmuch  as  they 
result  from  a  sin  in  nature's  action. 


270  QUESTION  XXI 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  end  is  twofold;  the  last  end,  and  the 
proximate  end.  In  the  sin  of  nature,  the  action  does 
indeed  fail  in  respect  of  the  last  end,  which  is  the  perfection 
of  the  thing  generated ;  but  it  does  not  fail  in  respect  of  any 
proximate  end  whatever;  since  when  nature  works  it  forms 
something.  In  like  manner,  the  sin  of  the  will  always  fails 
as  regards  the  last  end  intended,  because  no  voluntary  evil 
action  can  be  ordained  to  happiness,  which  is  the  last  end: 
and  yet  it  does  not  fail  in  respect  of  some  proximate  end: 
intended  and  achieved  by  the  will.  Wherefore  also,  since 
the  very  intention  of  this  end  is  ordained  to  the  last  end, 
this  same  intention  may  be  right  or  sinful. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Each  thing  is  ordained  to  its  end  by  its 
action:  and  therefore  sin,  which  consists  in  straying  from 
the  order  to  the  end,  consists  properly  in  an  action.  On 
the  other  hand,  punishment  regards  the  person  of  the 
sinner,  as  was  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XLVIII.,  A.  5, 
ad  4;  A.  6,  ad  3). 

Second  Article. 

whether  a  human  action  deserves  praise  or  blame,  by 
reason  of  its  being  good  or  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — ■ 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  human  action  does  not 
deserve  praise  or  blame  by  reason  of  its  being  good  or  evil. 
For  sin  happens  even  in  things  done  by  nature  {Ethic,  ii.). 
And  yet  natural  things  are  not  deserving  of  praise  or  blame 
{Ethic,  iii.).  Therefore  a  human  action  does  not  deserve 
blame,  by  reason  of  its  being  evil  or  sinful;  and,  conse- 
quently, neither  does  it  deserve  praise,  by  reason  of  its  being 
good. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  just  as  sin  occurs  in  moral  actions,  so 
does  it  happen  in  the  productions  of  art :  because  as  stated 
in  Phys.  ii.,  it  is  a  sin  in  a  grammarian  to  write  badly,  and 
in  a  doctor  to  give  the  wrong  medicine.  But  the  artist  is  not 
blamed  for  making  something  bad:  because  the  artist's 
work  is  such,  that  he  can  produce  a  good  or  a  bad  thing, 
just  as  he  lists.     Therefore  it  seems  that  neither  is  there 


ACTIONS  DESERVE  PRAISE  OR  BLAME       27J 

any  reason  for  blaming  a  moral  action,  in  the  fact  that  it 
is  evil. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Dionysius  says  {Div.  Nom.  iv.)  that  evil 
is  weak  and  incapable.  But  weakness  or  inability  either 
takes  away  or  diminishes  guilt.  Therefore  a  human  action 
does  not  incur  guilt  from  being  evil. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (De  Virt.  et  Vit.  i.) 
that  virtuous  deeds  deserve  praise,  while  deeds  that  are  opposed 
to  virtue  deserve  censure  and  blame.  But  good  actions  are 
virtuous;  because  virtue  makes  that  which  has  it  good,  and 
makes  its  operation  good  :  wherefore  actions  opposed  to 
virtue  are  evil.  Therefore  a  human  action  deserves  praise 
or  blame,  through  being  good  or  evil. 

/  answer  that,  Just  as  evil  is  more  comprehensive  than 
sin,  so  is  sin  more  comprehensive  than  blame.  For  an 
action  is  said  to  deserve  praise  or  blame,  from  its  being 
imputed  to  the  agent:  since  to  praise  or  to  blame  mean 
nothing  else  than  to  impute  to  someone  the  malice  or  good- 
ness of  his  action.  Now  an  action  is  imputed  to  an  agent, 
when  it  is  in  his  power,  so  that  he  has  dominion  over  it :  and 
this  is  the  case  in  all  voluntary  acts :  because  it  is  through 
his  will  that  man  has  dominion  over  his  actions,  as  was 
made  clear  above  (Q.  I.,  AA.  i,  2).  Hence  it  follows  that 
good  or  evil,  in  voluntary  actions  alone,  renders  them 
worthy  of  praise  or  blame:  and  in  suchlike  actions,  evil, 
sin  and  guilt  are  one  and  the  same  thing. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Natural  actions  are  not  in  the  power  of 
the  natural  agent:  since  the  action  of  nature  is  determinate. 
And,  therefore,  although  there  be  sin  in  natural  actions, 
there  is  no  blame. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Reason  stands  in  different  relations  to  the 
productions  of  art,  and  to  moral  actions.  In  matters  of 
art,  reason  is  directed  to  a  particular  end,  which  is  some- 
thing devised  by  reason:  whereas  in  moral  matters,  it  is 
directed  to  the  general  end  of  all  human  life.  Now  a 
particular  end  is  subordinate  to  the  general  end.  Since 
therefore  sin  is  a  departure  from  the  order  to  the  end,  as 
stated  above  (A.  i),  sin  may  occur  in  two  ways,  in  a  pro- 


272  QUESTION  XXI 

duction  of  art.  First,  by  a  departure  from  the  particular 
end  intended  by  the  artist:  and  this  sin  will  be  proper  to 
the  art ;  for  instance,  if  an  artist  produce  a  bad  thing,  while 
intending  to  produce  something  good ;  or  produce  something 
good,  while  intending  to  produce  something  bad.  Secondly, 
by  a  departure  from  the  general  end  of  human  life :  and  then 
he  will  be  said  to  sin,  if  he  intend  to  produce  a  bad  work, 
and  does  so  in  effect,  so  that  another  is  taken  in  thereby. 
But  this  sin  is  not  proper  to  the  artist  as  such,  but  as  a  man. 
Consequently  for  the  former  sin  the  artist  is  blamed  as  an 
artist;  while  for  the  latter  he  is  blamed  as  a  man. — ^On  the 
other  hand,  in  moral  matters,  where  we  take  into  considera- 
tion the  order  of  reason  to  the  general  end  of  human  life, 
sin  and  evil  are  always  due  to  a  departure  from  the  order 
of  reason  to  the  general  end  of  human  life.  Wherefore 
man  is  blamed  for  such  a  sin,  both  as  man  and  as  a  moral 
being.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  vi.)  that  in 
art,  he  who  voluntarily  sins  is  the  better  man  ;  hut  in  prudence, 
he  is  the  worse,  just  as  is  the  case  in  the  moral  virtues,  which 
prudence  directs. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Weakness  that  occurs  in  voluntary  evils, 
is  subject  to  man's  power:  wherefore  it  neither  takes  away 
nor  diminishes  guilt. 

Third  Article. 

whether  a  human  action  is  meritorious  or  demerit- 
orious, in  so  far  as  it  is  good  or  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — ■ 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  human  action  is  not  merit- 
orious or  demeritorious  on  account  of  its  goodness  or 
malice.  For  we  speak  of  merit  or  demerit  in  relation  to 
retribution,  which  has  no  place  save  in  matters  relating  to 
another  person.  But  good  or  evil  actions  are  not  all  re- 
lated to  another  person,  for  some  are  related  to  the  person 
of  the  agent.  Therefore  not  every  good  or  evil  human  action 
is  meritorious  or  demeritorious. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  No  one  deserves  punishment  or  reward 


MERIT  AND  DEMERIT  273 

for  doing  as  he  chooses  with  that  of  which  he  is  master: 
thus  if  a  man  destroys  what  belongs  to  him,  he  is  not 
punished,  as  if  he  had  destroyed  what  belongs  to  another. 
But  man  is  master  of  his  own  actions.  Therefore  a  man 
does  not  merit  punishment  or  reward,  through  putting  his 
action  to  a  good  or  evil  purpose. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  a  man  acquire  some  good  for  himself, 
he  does  not  on  that  account  deserve  to  be  benefited  by 
another  man:  and  the  same  applies  to  evil.  Now  a  good 
action  is  itself  a  kind  of  good  and  perfection  of  the  agent: 
while  an  inordinate  action  is  his  evil.  Therefore  a  man 
does  not  merit  or  demerit,  from  the  fact  that  he  does  a 
good  or  an  evil  deed. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Isa.  iii.  10,  11):  Say  to  the 
just  man  that  it  is  well ;  for  he  shall  eat  the  fruit  of  his  doings. 
Wo  to  the  wicked  unto  evil ;  for  the  reward  of  his  hands  shall 
he  given  him. 

I  answer  that.  We  speak  of  merit  and  demerit,  in  relation 
to  retribution,  rendered  according  to  justice.  Now,  retri- 
bution according  to  justice  is  rendered  to  a  man,  by  reason 
of  his  having  done  something  to  another's  advantage  or 
hurt.  It  must,  moreover,  be  observed  that  every  in- 
dividual member  of  a  society  is,  in  a  fashion,  a  part  and 
member  of  the  whole  society.  Wherefore,  any  good  or 
evil,  done  to  the  member  of  a  society,  redounds  on  the 
whole  society:  thus,  who  hurts  the  hand,  hurts  the  man. 
When,  therefore,  anyone  does  good  or  evil  to  another  in- 
dividual, there  is  a  twofold  measure  of  merit  or  demerit  in 
his  action:  first,  in  respect  of  the  retribution  owed  to  him 
by  the  individual  to  whom  he  has  done  good  or  harm; 
secondly,  in  respect  of  the  retribution  owed  to  him  by  the 
whole  of  society. — Now  when  a  man  ordains  his  action 
directly  for  the  good  or  evil  of  the  whole  society,  retribution 
is  owed  to  him,  before  and  above  all,  by  the  whole  society; 
secondarily,  by  all  the  parts  of  society.  Whereas  when  a 
man  does  that  which  conduces  to  his  own  benefit  or  dis- 
advantage, then  again  is  retribution  owed  to  him,  in  so  far 
as  this  too  affects  the  community,  forasmuch  as  he  is  a 

II.  I  18 


274  QUESTION  XXI 

part  of  society:  although  retribution  is  not  due  to  him,  in 
so  far  as  it  conduces  to  the  good  or  harm  of  an  individual, 
who  is  identical  with  the  agent;  unless,  perchance,  he  owe 
retribution  to  himself,  by  a  sort  of  resemblance,  in  so  far 
as  man  is  said  to  be  just  to  himself. 

It  is  therefore  evident  that  a  good  or  evil  action  deserves 
praise  or  blame,  in  so  far  as  it  is  in  the  power  of  the  will: 
that  it  is  right  or  sinful,  according  to  it  is  ordained  to  the 
end ;  and  that  its  merit  or  demerit  depend  on  the  retribution 
of  justice  to  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  A  man's  good  or  evil  actions,  although  not 
ordained  to  the  good  or  evil  of  another  individual,  are 
nevertheless  ordained  to  the  good  or  evil  of  another,  i.e., 
the  community. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Man  is  master  of  his  actions;  and  yet,  in 
so  far  as  he  belongs  to  another,  i.e.,  the  community,  of  which 
he  forms  part,  he  merits  or  demerits,  inasmuch  as  he  dis- 
poses his  actions  well  or  ill:  just  as  if  he  were  to  dispense 
well  or  ill  other  belongings  of  his,  in  respect  of  which  he  is 
bound  to  serve  the  community. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  very  good  or  evil,  which  a  man  does 
to  himself  by  his  action,  redounds  to  the  community,  as 
stated  above. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  a  human  action  is  meritorious  or  demerit- 
orious before  god,  according  as  it  is   good  or 

EVIL  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  1.  It  seems  that  man's  actions,  good  or  evil, 
are  not  meritorious  or  demeritorious  in  sight  of  God. 
Because,  as  stated  above  (A.  3),  merit  and  demerit  imply 
relation  to  retribution  for  good  or  harm  done  to  another. 
But  a  man's  action,  good  or  evil,  does  no  good  or  harm  to 
God;  for  it  is  written  (Job  xxxv.  6,  7):  //  thou  sin,  what 
shall  thou  hurt  Him  ?  .  .  .  And  if  thou  do  justly,  what  shall 
thou  give  Him  .^  Therefore  a  human  action,  good  or  evil, 
is  not  meritorious  or  demeritorious  in  the  sight  of  God. 


MERIT  AND  DEMERIT  275 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  an  instrument  acquires  no  merit  or  de- 
merit in  the  sight  of  him  that  uses  it;  because  the  entire 
action  of  the  instrument  belongs  to  the  user.  Now  when 
man  acts  he  is  the  instrument  of  the  Divine  power  which  is 
the  principal  cause  of  his  action;  hence  it  is  written  (Isa.  x. 
15) :  Shall  the  axe  boast  itselj  against  him  that  cutteth  with  it  ? 
Or  shall  the  saw  exalt  itself  against  him  hy  whom  it  is  drawn  ? 
where  man  while  acting  is  evidently  compared  to  an  instru- 
ment. Therefore  man  merits  or  demerits  nothing  in  God's 
sight,  by  good  or  evil  deeds. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  a  human  action  acquires  merit  or  demerit 
through  being  ordained  to  someone  else.  But  not  all 
human  actions  are  ordained  to  God.  Therefore  not  every 
good  or  evil  action  acquires  merit  or  demerit  in  God's  sight. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Eccles.  xii.  14):  All  things 
that  are  done,  God  will  bring  into  judgment  .  .  .  whether  it  be 
good  or  evil.  Now  judgment  implies  retribution,  in  respect 
of  which  we  speak  of  merit  and  demerit.  Therefore  every 
human  action,  both  good  and  evil,  acquires  merit  or  demerit 
in  God's  sight. 

/  ansiver  that,  A  human  action,  as  stated  above  (A.  3), 
acquires  merit  or  demerit,  through  being  ordained  to  some- 
one else,  either  by  reason  of  himself,  or  by  reason  of  the 
community:  and  in  each  way,  our  actions,  good  and  evil, 
acquire  merit  or  demerit  in  the  sight  of  God.  On  the  part  of 
God  Himself,  inasmuch  as  He  is  man's  last  end;  and  it  is 
our  duty  to  refer  all  our  actions  to  the  last  end,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XIX.,  A.  10).  Consequently  whoever  does  an 
evil  deed,  not  referrible  to  God,  does  not  give  God  the  honour 
due  to  Him  as  our  last  end. — On  the  part  of  the  whole 
community  of  the  universe,  because  in  every  community,  he 
who  governs  the  community,  cares,  first  of  all,  for  the 
common  good ;  wherefore  it  is  his  business  to  award  retribu- 
tion for  such  things  as  are  done  well  or  ill  in  the  community. 
Now  God  is  the  governor  and  ruler  of  the  whole  universe,  as 
stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  CIII.,  x\.  5):  and  especially  of 
rational  creatures.  Consequently  it  is  evident  that  human 
actions  acquire  merit  or  demerit  in  reference  to  Him:  else 


276  QUESTION  XXI 

it  would  follow  that  human  actions  are  no  business  of 
God's. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  God  in  Himself  neither  gains  nor  loses  any- 
thing by  the  action  of  man:  but  man,  for  his  part,  takes 
something  from  God,  or  offers  something  to  Him,  when  he 
observes  or  does  not  observe  the  order  instituted  by  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Man  is  so  moved,  as  an  instrument,  by  God, 
that,  at  the  same  time,  be  moves  himself  by  his  free-will,  as 
was  explained  above  (Q.  IX.,  A.  6  ^i  3).  Consequently,  by 
his  action,  he  acquires  merit  or  demerit  in  God's  sight. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Man  is  not  ordained  to  the  body  politic, 
according  to  all  that  he  is  and  has ;  and  so  it  does  not  follow 
that  every  action  of  his  acquires  merit  or  demerit  in  relation 
to  the  body  politic.  But  all  that  man  is,  and  can,  and  has, 
must  be  referred  to  God :  and  therefore  every  action  of  man , 
whether  good  or  bad,  acquires  merit  or  demerit  in  the  sight 
of  God,  as  far  as  the  action  itself  is  concerned. 


QUESTION  XXII. 

OF  THE  SUBJECT  OF  THE  SOUL'S  PASSIONS. 

[In  Three  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  passions  of  the  soul:  first,  in 
general;  secondly,  in  particular.  Taking  them  in  general, 
there  are  four  things  to  be  considered:  (i)  Their  subject: 
(2)  The  difference  between  them:  (3)  Their  mutual  relation- 
ship: (4)  Their  malice  and  goodness. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  three  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  there  is  any  passion  in  the  soul  ?  (2)  Whether 
passion  is  in  the  appetitive  rather  than  in  the  apprehensive 
part  ?  (3)  Whether  passion  is  in  the  sensitive  appetite  rather 
than  in  the  intellectual  appetite,  which  is  called  the  will  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  any  passion  is  in  the  soul  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  is  no  passion  in  the  soul. 
Because  passivity  belongs  to  matter.  But  the  soul  is  not 
composed  of  matter  and  form,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part 
(Q.  LXXV.,  A.  5).     Therefore  there  is  no  passion  in  the  soul. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  passion  is  movement,  as  is  stated  in 
Phys.  iii.  But  the  soul  is  not  moved,  as  is  proved  in  De 
Anima  i.     Therefore  passion  is  not  in  the  soul. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  passion  is  the  road  to  corruption;  since 
every  passion,  when  increased,  alters  the  substance,  as  is  stated 
in  Topic,  vi.  But  the  soul  is  incorruptible.  Therefore  no 
passion  is  in  the  soul. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  vii.  5):  When  we 

277 


278  QUESTION  XXII 

were  in  the  flesh,  the  passions  of  sins  which  were  by  the  law, 
did  work  in  our  members.  Now  sins  are,  properly  speaking, 
in  the  soul.  Therefore  passions  also,  which  are  described  as 
being  of  sins,  are  in  the  soul. 

I  answer  that,  The  word  passive  is  used  in  three  ways. 
First,  in  a  general  way,  according  as  whatever  receives 
something  is  passive,  although  nothing  is  taken  from  it: 
thus  we  may  say  that  the  air  is  passive  when  it  is  lit  up. 
But  this  is  to  be  perfected  rather  than  to  be  passive. 
Secondly,  the  word  passive  is  employed  in  its  proper  sense, 
when  something  is  received,  while  something  else  is  taken 
away :  and  this  happens  in  two  ways.  For  sometimes  that 
which  is  lost  is  unsuitable  to  the  thing:  thus  when  an 
animal's  body  is  healed,  it  is  said  to  be  passive,  because  it 
receives  health,  and  loses  sickness. — At  other  times  the 
contrary  occurs:  thus  to  ail  is  to  be  passive;  because  the 
ailment  is  received  and  health  is  lost.  And  here  we  have 
passion  in  its  most  proper  acceptation.  For  a  thing  is  said 
to  be  passive  from  its  being  drawn  to  the  agent :  and  when 
a  thing  recedes  from  what  is  suitable  to  it,  then  especially 
does  it  appear  to  be  drawn  to  something  else.  Moreover  in 
De  General,  iii.  we  find  it  stated  that  when  a  more  excellent 
thing  is  generated  from  a  less  excellent,  we  have  generation 
simply,  and  corruption  in  a  particular  respect :  whereas  the 
reverse  is  the  case,  when  from  a  more  excellent  thing,  a  less 
excellent  is  generated.  In  these  three  ways  it  happens  that 
passions  are  in  the  soul.  For  in  the  sense  of  mere  reception, 
we  speak  of  feeling  and  understanding  as  being  a  kind  of 
passion  (De  Anima  i.).  But  passion,  accompanied  by  the 
loss  of  something,  is  only  in  respect  of  a  bodily  transmuta- 
tion; wherefore  passion  properly  so  caUed  cannot  be  in  the 
soul,  save  accidentally,  in  so  far,  to  wit,  as  the  composite  is 
passive.  But  here  again  we  find  a  difference;  because  when 
this  transmutation  is  for  the  worse,  it  has  more  of  the  nature 
of  a  passion,  than  when  it  is  for  the  better:  hence  sorrow 
is  more  properly  a  passion  than  joy. 

T^eply  Obj.  i.  It  belongs  to  matter  to  be  passive  in  such  a 
way  as  to  lose  something  and  to  be  transmuted :  hence  this 


SUBJECT  OF  THE  SOUL'S  PASSIONS  279 

happens  only  in  those  things  that  are  composed  of  matter 
and  form.  But  passivity,  as  implying  mere  reception,  need 
not  be  in  matter,  but  can  be  in  anything  that  is  in  potenti- 
ality. Now,  though  the  soul  is  not  composed  of  matter  and 
form,  yet  it  has  something  of  potentiality,  in  respect  of 
which  it  is  competent  to  receive  or  to  be  passive,  according 
as  the  act  of  understanding  is  a  kind  of  passion,  as  stated  in 
De  Anima  iii. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  it  does  not  become  the  soul  in 
itself,  to  be  passive  and  to  be  moved,  yet  it  becomes  it 
accidentally,  as  stated  in  De  Anima  i. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  argument  is  true  of  passion  accom- 
panied by  transmutation  to  something  worse.  And  passion, 
in  this  sense,  is  unbecoming  to  the  soul,  except  accidentally: 
but  it  is  becoming  to  the  composite,  which  is  corruptible,  by 
reason  of  its  very  nature. 

Second  Article. 

whether  passion  is  in  the  appetitive  rather 
than  in  the  apprehensive  part  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  passion  is  in  the  apprehensive 
part  of  the  soul  rather  than  in  the  appetitive.  Because  that 
which  is  first  in  any  genus,  seems  to  rank  first  among  all 
things  that  are  in  that  genus,  and  to  be  their  cause,  as  is 
stated  in  Metaph.  ii.  Now  passion  is  found  to  be  in  the 
apprehensive,  before  being  in  the  appetitive  part:  for  the 
appetitive  part  is  not  affected  unless  there  be  a  previous 
passion  in  the  apprehensive  part.  Therefore  passion  is  in 
the  apprehensive  part  more  than  in  the  appetitive. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  what  is  more  active  is  less  passive;  for 
action  is  contrary  to  passion.  Now  the  appetitive  part  is 
more  active  than  the  apprehensive.  Therefore  it  seems  that 
passion  is  more  in  the  apprehensive  part. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  just  as  the  sensitive  appetite  is  the  power 
of  a  corporeal  organ,  so  is  the  power  of  sensitive  appre- 
hension.    But  passion  in  the  soul  occurs,  properly  speaking, 


28o  QUESTION  XXII 

in  respect  of  a  bodily  transmutation.  Therefore  passion  is 
not  more  in  the  appetitive  than  in  the  apprehensive  part. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  ix.)  that  the 
movements  of  the  soul,  which  the  Greeks  call  irdOi],  are  styled  by 
some  of  our  writers,  Cicero"^  for  instance,  disturbances  ;  by 
some,  affections  or  emotions  ;  while  others  rendering  the  Greek 
more  accurately,  call  them  passions.  From  this  it  is  evident 
that  the  passions  of  the  soul  are  the  same  as  affections.  But 
affections  manifestly  belong  to  the  appetitive,  and  not  to  the 
apprehensive  part.  Therefore  the  passions  are  in  the  appe- 
titive rather  than  in  the  apprehensive  part. 

I  answer  that.  As  we  have  already  stated  (A.  i)  the  word 
passion  implies  that  the  patient  is  drawn  to  that  which 
belongs  to  the  agent.  Now  the  soul  is  drawn  to  a  thing  by 
the  appetitive  power  rather  than  by  the  apprehensive  power : 
because  the  soul  has,  through  its  appetitive  power,  an  order 
to  things  as  they  are  in  themselves:  hence  the  Philosopher 
says  (Metaph.  vi.)  that  good  and  evil,  i.e.,  the  objects  of  the 
appetitive  power,  are  in  things  themselves.  On  the  other 
hand  the  apprehensive  power  is  not  drawn  to  a  thing,  as  it 
is  in  itself;  but  knows  it  by  reason  of  an  intention  of  the 
thing,  which  intention  it  has  in  itself,  or  receives  in  its  own 
way.  Hence  we  find  it  stated  (ibid.)  that  the  true  and  the 
false,  which  pertain  to  knowledge,  are  not  in  things,  but  in 
the  mind.  Consequently  it  is  evident  that  the  nature  of 
passion  is  consistent  with  the  appetitive,  rather  than  with 
the  apprehensive  part. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  In  things  relating  to  perfection  the  case  is 
the  opposite,  in  comparison  to  things  that  pertain  to  defect. 
Because  in  things  relating  to  perfection,  intensity  is  in 
proportion  to  the  approach  to  one  first  principle;  to  which 
the  nearer  a  thing  approaches,  the  more  intense  it  is.  Thus 
the  intensity  of  a  thing  possessed  of  light  depends  on  its 
approach  to  something  endowed  with  light  in  a  supreme 
degree,  to  which  the  nearer  a  thing  approaches,  the  more 
light   it   possesses.     But   in   things   that  relate   to   defect, 

*  Those  things  which  the  Greeks  call  Trddr],  we  prefer  to  call  disturb- 
ances rather  than  diseases  (Tusc.  iv.  5). 


SUBJECT  OF  THE  SOUL'S  PASSIONS  281 

intensity  depends,  not  on  approach  to  something  supreme, 
but  in  receding  from  that  which  is  perfect;  because  therein 
consists  the  very  notion  of  privation  and  defect.  Wherefore 
the  less  a  thing  recedes  from  that  which  stands  first,  the  less 
intense  it  is :  and  the  result  is  that  at  first  we  always  find 
some  small  defect,  which  afterwards  increases  as  it  goes  on. 
Now  passion  pertains  to  defect,  because  it  belongs  to  a  thing 
according  as  it  is  in  potentiality.  Wherefore  in  those  things 
that  approach  to  the  Supreme  Perfection,  i.e.,  to  God,  there 
is  but  little  potentiality  and  passion :  while  in  other  things, 
consequently,  there  is  more.  Hence  also,  in  the  supreme, 
i.e.,  the  apprehensive,  power  of  the  soul,  passion  is  found  less 
than  in  the  other  powers. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  appetitive  power  is  said  to  be  more 
active,  because  it  is,  more  than  the  apprehensive  power,  the 
principle  of  the  exterior  action :  and  this  from  the  very  fact 
that  it  is  more  passive,  through  being  related  to  things  as 
existing  in  themselves:  since  it  is  through  the  external 
action  that  we  come  into  contact  with  things. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  As  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  LXXVHL, 
A.  3),  the  organs  of  the  soul  can  be  changed  in  two  ways. 
First,  by  a  spiritual  change,  in  respect  of  which  the  organ 
receives  an  intention  of  the  object.  And  this  is  essential  to 
the  act  of  the  sensitive  apprehension :  thus  is  the  eye  changed 
by  the  object  visible,  not  by  being  coloured,  but  by  receiving 
an  intention  of  colour.  But  the  organs  are  receptive  of 
another  natural  change,  which  affects  their  natural  dis- 
position; for  instance,  when  they  become  hot  or  cold,  or 
undergo  some  similar  change.  And  whereas  this  kind  of 
change  is  accidental  to  the  act  of  the  sensitive  apprehension ; 
for  instance,  if  the  eye  be  wearied  through  gazing  intently 
at  something,  or  be  overcome  by  the  intensity  of  the  object : 
on  the  other  hand,  it  is  essential  to  the  act  of  the  sensitive 
appetite;  wherefore  the  material  element  in  the  definitions 
of  the  movements  of  the  appetitive  part,  is  the  natural 
change  of  the  organ;  for  instance,  anger  is  said  to  be  a 
kindling  of  the  blood  about  the  heart.  Hence  it  is  evident  that 
the  notion  of  passion  is  more  consistent  with  the  act  of  the 


282  QUESTION  XXII 

sensitive  appetite,  than  with  that  of  the  sensitive  appre- 
hension, although  both  are  actions  of  a  corporeal  organ. 


Third  Article. 

whether  passion  is  in  the  sensitive  appetite  rather 
than  in  the  intellectual  appetite,  which  is  called 

THE   WILL  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  passion  is  not  more  in  the 
sensitive  than  in  the  intellectual  appetite.  For  Dionysius 
declares  {Div.  Nom.  ii.)  Hierotheus  to  be  taught  by  a  kind  of 
yet  more  Godlike  instruction  ;  not  only  by  learning  Divine 
things,  but  also  by  suffering  (patiens)  them.  But  the  sensitive 
appetite  cannot  suffer  Divine  things,  since  its  object  is  the 
sensitive  good.  Therefore  passion  is  in  the  intellectual 
appetite,  just  as  it  is  also  in  the  sensitive  appetite. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  more  powerful  the  active  force,  the 
more  intense  the  passion.  But  the  object  of  the  intellectual 
appetite,  which  is  the  universal  good,  is  a  more  powerful 
active  force,  than  the  object  of  the  sensitive  appetite,  which 
is  a  particular  good.  Therefore  passion  is  more  consistent 
with  intellectual  than  with  the  sensitive  appetite. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  joy  and  love  are  said  to  be  passions.  But 
these  are  to  be  found  in  the  intellectual  and  not  only  in  the 
sensitive  appetite:  else  they  would  not  be  ascribed  by  the 
Scriptures  to  God  and  the  angels.  Therefore  the  passions 
are  not  more  in  the  sensitive  than  in  the  intellectual  appetite. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.), 
while  describing  the  animal  passions :  Passion  is  a  movement 
of  the  sensitive  appetite  when  we  imagine  good  or  evil :  in 
other  words,  passion  is  a  movement  of  the  irrational  soul, 
when  we  think  of  good  or  evil. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i)  passion  is  properly  to 
be  found  where  there  is  corporeal  transmutation.  This 
corporeal  transmutation  is  found  in  the  act  of  the  sensitive 
appetite,  and  is  not  only  spiritual,  as  in  the  sensitive  appre- 
hension, but  also  natural.    Now  there  is  no  need  for  corporeal 


SUBJECT  OF  THE  SOUL'S  PASSIONS  283 

transmutation  in  the  act  of  the  intellectual  appetite :  because 
this  appetite  is  not  exercised  by  means  of  a  corporeal  organ . 
It  is  therefore  evident  that  passion  is  more  properly  in  the 
act  of  the  sensitive  appetite,  than  in  that  of  the  intellectual 
appetite;  and  this  is  again  evident  from  the  definitions  of 
Damascene  quoted  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  By  suffering  Divine  things  is  meant  being 
well  affected  towards  them,  and  united  to  them  by  love: 
and  this  takes  place  without  any  alteration  in  the  body. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Intensity  of  passion  depends  not  only  on  the 
power  of  the  agent,  but  also  on  the  passibility  of  the  patient : 
because  things  that  are  disposed  to  passion,  suffer  much 
even  from  petty  agents.  Therefore  although  the  object  of 
the  intellectual  appetite  has  greater  activity  than  the  object 
of  the  sensitive  appetite,  yet  the  sensitive  appetite  is  more 
passive. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  When  love  and  joy  and  the  like  are  ascribed 
to  God  or  the  angels,  or  to  man  in  respect  of  his  intellectual 
appetite,  they  signify  simple  acts  of  the  will  having  like 
effects,  but  without  passion.  Hence  Augustine  says  (De 
Civ.  Dei  ix.):  The  holy  angels  feel  no  anger  while  they 
punish  .  .  .,  no  fellow-feeling  with  misery  while  they  relieve  the 
unhappy  :  and  yet  ordinary  human  speech  is  wont  to  ascrihe 
to  them  also  these  passions  hy  name,  because,  although  they 
have  none  of  our  weakness,  their  acts  hear  a  certain  resemhlance 
to  ours. 


QUESTION  XXIII. 

HOW  THE  PASSIONS  DIFFER  FROM  ONE  ANOTHER. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  how  the  passions  differ  from  one 
another:  and  under  this  head  there  are  four  points  of 
inquiry:  (i). Whether  the  passions  of  the  concupiscible  part 
are  different  from  those  of  the  irascible  part  ?  (2)  Whether 
the  contrariety  of  passions  in  the  irascible  part  is  based  on 
the  contrariety  of  good  and  evil  ?  (3)  Whether  there  is  any 
passion  that  has  no  contrary  ?  (4)  Whether,  in  the  same 
power,  there  are  any  passions,  differing  in  species,  but  not 
contrary  to  one  another  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  the  passions  of  the  concupiscible  part  are 
different  from  those  of  the  irascible  part  ? 

We  proceed  thiis  to  the  First  Article  : — ■ 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  same  passions  are  in  the 
irascible  and  concupiscible  parts.  For  the  Philosopher  says 
{Ethic,  ii.)  that  the  passions  of  the  soul  are  those  emotions 
which  are  followed  by  joy  or  sorrow.  But  joy  and  sorrow  are 
in  the  concupiscible  part.  Therefore  all  the  passions  are  in 
the  concupiscible  part,  and  not  some  in  the  irascible,  others 
in  the  concupiscible  part. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  on  the  words  of  Matth.  xiii.  33,  The 
kingdom  of  heaven  is  like  to  leaven,  etc.,  the  gloss  of  Jerome 
says :  We  should  have  prudence  in  the  reason ;  hatred  of  vice,  in 
the  irascible  faculty ;  desire  of  virtue,  in  the  concupiscible  part. 
But  hatred  is  in  the  concupiscible  faculty,  as  also  is  love,  of 

284 


HOW  PASSIONS  DIFFER  FROM  ONE  ANOTHER    285 

which  it  is  the  contrary,  as  is  stated  in  Topic,  ii.  Therefore 
the  same  passion  is  in  the  concupiscible  and  irascible 
faculties. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  passions  and  actions  differ  specifically 
according  to  their  objects.  But  the  objects  of  the  irascible 
and  concupiscible  passions  are  the  same,  viz.,  good  and  evil. 
Therefore  the  same  passions  are  in  the  irascible  and  con- 
cupiscible faculties. 

On  the  contrary,  The  acts  of  different  powers,  differ  in 
species ;  for  instance,  to  see,  and  to  hear.  But  the  irascible 
and  the  concupiscible  are  two  powers  into  which  the  sensi- 
tive appetite  is  divided,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q. 
LXXXI.,  A.  2).  Therefore,  since  the  passions  are  move- 
ments of  the  sensitive  appetite,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXII., 
A.  3),  the  passions  of  the  irascible  faculty  are  specifically 
distinct  from  those  of  the  concupiscible  part. 

/  answer  that,  The  passions  of  the  irascible  part  differ  in 
species  from  those  of  the  concupiscible  faculty.  For  since 
different  powers  have  different  objects,  as  stated  in  the  First 
Part  (Q.  LXXVIL,  A.  3),  the  passions  of  different  powers 
must  of  necessity  be  referred  to  different  objects.  Much 
more,  therefore,  do  the  passions  of  different  faculties  differ 
in  species:  since  a  greater  difference  in  the  object  is  required 
to  diversify  the  species  of  the  powders,  than  to  diversify  the 
species  of  passions  or  actions.  For  just  as  in  the  physical 
order,  diversity  of  genus  arises  from  diversity  in  the  poten- 
tiality of  matter,  while  diversity  of  species  arises  from 
diversity  of  form  in  the  same  matter;  so  in  the  acts  of  the 
soul,  those  that  belong  to  different  powers,  differ  not  only  in 
species  but  also  in  genus,  while  acts  and  passions  regarding 
different  specific  objects,  included  under  the  one  common 
object  of  a  single  power,  differ  as  the  species  of  that  genus. 

In  order,  therefore,  to  discern  which  passions  are  in  the 
irascible,  and  which  in  the  concupiscible,  we  must  take  the 
object  of  each  of  these  powers.  For  we  have  stated  in  the 
First  Part  (Q.  LXXXI.,  A.  2)  that  the  object  of  the  con- 
cupiscible power  is  sensible  good  or  evil,  simply  apprehended 
as  such,  which  causes  pleasure  or  pain.     But,  since  the  soul 


286  QUESTION  XXIII 

must,  of  necessity,  experience  difficulty  or  struggle  at  times, 
in  acquiring  some  such  good,  or  in  avoiding  some  such  evil, 
in  so  far  as  such  good  or  evil  is  more  than  our  animal  nature 
can  easily  acquire  or  avoid;  therefore  this  very  good  or  evil, 
inasmuch  as  it  is  of  an  arduous  or  difficult  nature,  is  the 
object  of  the  irascible  faculty.  Therefore  whatever  passions 
regard  good  or  evil  absolutely,  belong  to  the  concupiscible 
power;  for  instance,  joy,  sorrow,  love,  hatred  and  suchlike: 
whereas  those  passions  which  regard  good  or  bad  as  arduous, 
through  being  difficult  to  obtain  or  avoid,  belong  to  the 
irascible  faculty;  such  are  daring,  fear,  hope  and  the  like. 

Reply  Ob],  i.  As  stated  in  the  First  Part  (loc.  cit.),  the 
irascible  faculty  is  bestowed  on  animals,  in  order  to  remove 
the  obstacles  that  hinder  the  concupiscible  power  from 
tending  towards  its  object,  either  by  making  some  good 
difficult  to  obtain,  or  by  making  some  evil  hard  to  avoid. 
The  result  is  that  all  the  irascible  passions  terminate  in  the 
concupiscible  passions:  and  thus  it  is  that  joy  and  sorrow, 
which  are  concupiscible  passions,  follow  from  those  passions 
which  are  in  the  concupiscible  faculty. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Jerome  ascribes  hatred  of  vice  to  the 
irascible  faculty,  not  by  reason  of  hatred,  which  is  properly 
a  concupiscible  passion;  but  on  account  of  the  struggle, 
which  belongs  to  the  irascible  power. 

Reply.  Ohj  3.  Good,  inasmuch  as  it  is  delightful,  moves 
the  concupiscible  power.  But  if  it  prove  difficult  to  obtain, 
from  this  very  fact  it  has  a  certain  contrariety  to  the  con- 
cupiscible power:  and  hence  the  need  of  another  power 
tending  to  that  good.  The  same  applies  to  evil.  And  this 
power  is  the  irascible  faculty .  Consequently  the  concupiscible 
passions  are  specifically  different  from  the  irascible  passions. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  contrariety  of  the  irascible  passions  is 
based  on  the  contrariety  of  good  and  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus-  to  the  Second  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  contrariety  of  the  irascible 
passions  is  based  on  no  other  contrariety  than  that  of  good 


HOW  PASSIONS  DIFFER  FROM  ONE  ANOTHER     287 

and  evil.  For  the  irascible  passions  are  ordained  to  the  con- 
cup  iscible  passions,  as  stated  above  (A.  i  ad  i).  But  the 
contrariety  of  the  concupiscible  passions  is  no  other  than  that 
of  good  and  evil;  take,  for  instance,  love  and  hatred,  joy  and 
sorrow.     Therefore  the  same  applies  to  the  irascible  passions. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  passions  differ  according  to  their  objects; 
just  as  movements  differ  according  to  their  termini.  But 
there  is  no  other  contrariety  of  movements,  except  that  of 
the  termini,  as  is  stated  in  Phys.  v.  Therefore  there  is  no 
other  contrariety  of  passions,  save  that  of  the  objects.  Now 
the  object  of  the  appetite  is  good  or  evil.  Therefore  in  no 
appetitive  power  can  there  be  contrariety  of  passions  other 
than  that  of  good  and  evil. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  every  passion  of  the  soul  is  by  way  of 
approach  and  withdrawal,  as  Avicenna  declares  in  his  sixth 
book  of  Physics  (De  Anima  ii.).  Now  approach  results  from 
the  apprehension  of  good ;  withdrawal,  from  the  apprehension 
of  evil:  since  just  as  good  is  what  all  desire  (Ethic,  i.),  so  evil 
is  what  all  shun.  Therefore,  in  the  passions  of  the  soul,  there 
can  be  no  other  contrariety  than  that  of  good  and  evil. 

On  the  contrary,  Fear  and  daring  are  contrary  to  one 
another,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iii.  But  fear  and  daring  do  not 
differ  in  respect  of  good  and  evil :  because  each  regards  some 
kind  of  evil.  Therefore  not  every  contrariety  of  the  irascible 
passions  is  that  of  good  and  evil. 

/  answer  that,  Passion  is  a  kind  of  movement,  as  stated  in 
Phys.  iii.  Therefore  contrariety  of  passions  is  based  on 
contrariety  of  movements  or  changes.  Now  there  is  a  two- 
fold contrariety  in  changes  and  movements,  as  stated  in 
Phys.  V.  One  is  according  to  approach  and  withdrawal  in 
respect  of  the  same  term:  and  this  contrariety  belongs 
properly  to  changes,  i.e.,  to  generation,  which  is  a  change 
to  being,  and  to  corruption,  which  is  change  from  being. 
The  other  contrariety  is  according  to  opposition  of  termini, 
and  belongs  properly  to  movements :  thus  whitening,  which 
is  movement  from  black  to  white,  is  contrary  to  blackening, 
which  is  movement  from  white  to  black. 

Accordingly  there  is  a  twofold  contrariety  in  the  passions 


288  QUESTION  XXIII 

of  the  soul:  one,  according  to  contrariety  of  objects,  i.e.,  of 
good  and  evil;  the  other,  according  to  approach  and  with- 
drawal in  respect  of  the  same  term.  In  the  concupiscible 
passions  the  former  contrariety  alone  is  to  be  found;  viz., 
that  which  is  based  on  the  objects:  whereas  in  the  irascible 
passions,  we  find  both  forms  of  contrariety.  The  reason  of 
this  is  that  the  object  of  the  concupiscible  faculty,  as  stated 
above  (A.  i),  is  sensible  good  or  evil  considered  absolutely. 
Now  good,  as  such,  cannot  be  a  term  wherefrom,  but  only  a 
term  whereto,  since  nothing  shuns  good  as  such,  on  the 
contrary,  all  things  desire  it.  In  like  manner,  nothing 
desires  evil,  as  such ;  but  all  things  shun  it :  wherefore  evil 
cannot  have  the  aspect  of  a  term  whereto,  but  only  of  a 
term  wherefrom.  Accordingly  every  concupiscible  passion 
in  respect  of  good,  tends  to  it,  as  love,  desire  and  joy;  while 
every  concupiscible  passion  in  respect  of  evil,  tends  from 
it,  as  hatred,  avoidance  or  dislike,  and  sorrow.  Wherefore, 
in  the  concupiscible  passions,  there  can  be  no  contrariety 
of  approach  and  withdrawal  in  respect  of  the  same  object. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  object  of  the  irascible  faculty,  is 
sensible  good  or  evil,  considered  not  absolutely,  but  under 
the  aspect  of  difficulty  or  arduousness.  Now  the  good 
which  is  difficult  or  arduous,  considered  as  good,  is  of  such  a 
nature  as  to  produce  in  us  a  tendency  to  it,  which  tendency 
pertains  to  the  passion  of  hope;  whereas,  considered  as 
arduous  or  difficult,  it  makes  us  turn  from  it;  and  this 
pertains  to  the  passion  of  despair.  In  like  manner  the 
arduous  evil,  considered  as  an  evil,  has  the  aspect  of  some- 
thing to  be  shunned;  and  this  belongs  to  the  passion  oifear  : 
but  it  also  contains  a  reason  for  tending  to  it,  as  attempting 
something  arduous,  whereby  to  escape  being  subject  to  evil; 
and  this  tendency  is  called  daring.  Consequently  in  the 
irascible  passions  we  find  contrariety  in  respect  of  good  and 
evil  (as  between  hope  and  fear) :  and  also  contrariety  accord- 
ing to  approach  and  withdrawal  in  respect  of  the  same  term 
(as  between  daring  and  fear). 

From  what  has  been  said  the  replies  to  the  objections  are 
evident. 


HOW  PASSIONS  DIFFER  FROM  ONE  ANOTHER    289 


Third  Article, 
whether  any  passion  of  the  soul  has  no  contrary  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  every  passion  of  the  soul  has  a 
contrary.  For  every  passion  of  the  soul  is  either  in  the 
irascible  or  in  the  concupiscible  faculty,  as  stated  above 
(A.  i).  But  both  kinds  of  passions  have  their  respective 
modes  of  contrariety.  Therefore  every  passion  of  the  soul 
has  its  contrary. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  every  passion  of  the  soul  has  either  good 
or  evil  for  its  object;  for  these  are  the  common  objects  of 
the  appetitive  part.  But  a  passion  having  good  for  its 
object,  is  contrary  to  a  passion  having  evil  for  its  object. 
Therefore  every  passion  has  a  contrary. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  every  passion  of  the  soul  is  in  respect 
of  approach  or  withdrawal,  as  stated  above  (A.  2).  But 
every  approach  has  a  corresponding  contrary  withdrawal, 
and  vice  versa.  Therefore  every  passion  of  the  soul  has  a 
contrary. 

On  the  contrary,  Anger  is  a  passion  of  the  soul.  But  no 
passion  is  set  down  as  being  contrary  to  anger,  as  stated  in 
Ethic,  iv.     Therefore  not  every  passion  has  a  contrary. 

/  answer  that,  The  passion  of  anger  is  peculiar  in  this,  that 
it  cannot  have  a  contrary;  neither  according  to  approach 
and  withdrawal,  nor  according  to  the  contrariety  of  good 
and  evil.  For  anger  is  caused  by  a  difficult  evil  alread}^ 
present :  and  when  such  an  evil  is  present,  the  appetite  must 
needs  either  succumb,  so  that  it  does  not  go  beyond  the 
limits  of  sorrow,  which  is  a  concupiscible  passion;  or  else  it 
has  a  movement  of  attack  on  the  hurtful  evil,  which  move- 
ment is  that  of  anger.  But  it  cannot  have  a  movement  of 
withdrawal:  because  the  evil  is  supposed  to  be  already 
present  or  past.  Thus  no  passion  is  contrary  to  anger 
according  to  contrariety  of  approach  or  withdrawal. 

In  like  manner  neither  can  there  be  according  to  con- 
trariety of  good  and  evil.     Because  the  opposite  of  present 

II.  I  19 


290  QUESTION  XXIII 

evil  is  good  obtained,  which  can  no  longer  have  the  aspect 
of  arduousness  or  difficulty.  Nor,  when  once  good  is  ob- 
tained, does  there  remain  any  other  movement,  except  the 
appetite's  repose  in  the  good  obtained ;  which  repose  belongs 
to  joy,  which  is  a  passion  of  the  concupiscible  faculty. 

Accordingly  no  movement  of  the  soul  can  be  contrary  to 
the  movement  of  anger,  and  nothing  else  than  cessation  from 
its  movement  is  contrary  thereto ;  thus  the  Philosopher  says 
(Rhetor,  ii.)  that  calm  is  contrary  to  anger,  by  opposition  not 
of  contrariety  but  of  negation  or  privation. 

From  what  has  been  said  the  replies  to  the  objections  are 

evident. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  in  the  same  power,  there  are  any  passions, 
specifically  different,  but  not  contrary  to  one 

ANOTHER  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — • 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  cannot  be,  in  the  same 
power,  specifically  different  passions  that  are  not  contrary 
to  one  another.  For  the  passions  of  the  soul  differ  according 
to  their  objects.  Now  the  objects  of  the  soul's  passions  are 
good  and  evil;  and  on  this  distinction  is  based  the  con- 
trariety of  the  passions.  Therefore  no  passions  of  the  same 
power,  that  are  not  contrary  to  one  another,  differ  specifically. 
Ohj.  2.  Further,  difference  of  species  implies  a  difference 
of  form.  But  every  difference  of  form,  is  in  respect  of  some 
contrariety,  as  stated  in  Metaph.  x.  Therefore  passions  of 
the  same  power,  that  are  not  contrary  to  one  another,  do 
not  differ  specifically. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  since  every  passion  consists  in  approach 
or  withdrawal  in  respect  of  good  or  evil,  it  seems  that  every 
difference  in  the  passions  of  the  soul  must  needs  arise  from 
the  difference  of  good  and  evil;  or  from  the  difference  of 
approach  and  withdrawal;  or  from  degrees  in  approach 
or  withdrawal.  Now  the  first  two  differences  cause 
contrariety  in  the  passions  of  the  soul,  as  stated  above 
(A.  2):  whereas  the  third  difference  does  not  diversify  the 


HOW  PASSIONS  DIFFER  FROM  ONE  ANOTHER    291 

species;  else  the  species  of  the  soul's  passions  would  be 
infinite.  Therefore  it  is  not  possible  for  passions  of  the  same 
power  to  differ  in  species,  without  being  contrary  to  one 
another. 

On  the  contrary,  Love  and  joy,  differ  in  species,  and  are  in 
the  concupiscible  power;  and  yet  they  are  not  contrary  to 
one  another;  rather,  in  fact,  one  causes  the  other.  There- 
fore in  the  same  power  there  are  passions  that  differ  in 
species  without  being  contrary  to  one  another. 

/  answer  that,  Passions  differ  according  to  their  active 
causes,  which  are  the  objects  of  the  soul's  passions.  Now 
active  causes  are  differentiated  in  two  ways :  first  in  respect 
of  their  species  or  nature;  thus  fire  differs  from  water: 
secondly  in  respect  of  a  difference  in  their  active  powers. 
And  the  difference  of  active  or  motive  causes,  in  respect  of 
their  motive  powers,  can  be  applied  to  the  passions  of  the 
soul,  in  a  like  manner  as  to  natural  agents.  For  every 
mover,  in  a  fashion,  either  draws  the  patient  to  itself,  or 
drives  it  back.  Now  in  drawing  it  to  itself,  it  does  three 
things  in  the  patient.  Because,  in  the  first  place,  it  gives 
the  patient  an  inclination  or  aptitude  to  tend  to  the  mover : 
thus  a  light  body,  which  is  above,  bestows  lightness  on  the 
body  generated,  so  that  it  has  an  inclination  or  aptitude  to 
be  above.  Secondly,  if  the  generated  body  be  outside  its 
proper  place,  the  mover  gives  it  movement  towards  that 
place. — Thirdly,  it  makes  it  to  rest,  when  it  shall  have 
come  to  its  proper  place:  since  to  the  same  cause  are  due, 
both  rest  in  a  place,  and  the  movement  to  that  place.  The 
same  applies  to  the  cause  of  repulsion. 

Now,  in  the  movements  of  the  appetitive  faculty,  good 
has,  as  it  were,  a  force  of  attraction,  while  evil  has  a 
force  of  repulsion.  In  the  first  place,  therefore,  good 
causes,  in  the  appetitive  power,  a  certain  inclination, 
aptitude  or  connaturalness  in  respect  of  good:  and  this 
belongs  to  the  passion  of  love  :  the  corresponding  contrary 
of  which  is  hatred  in  respect  of  evil. — Secondly,  if  the  good  be 
not  yet  possessed,  it  causes  in  the  appetite  a  movement 
towards  the  attainment  of  the  good  beloved :  and  this  belongs 


292  QUESTION  XXIII 

to^the  passion  of  desire  or  concupiscence  :  and  contrary  to 
it,  in  respect  of  evil,  is  the  passion  of  avoidance  or  dislike. — - 
Thirdly,  when  the  good  is  obtained,  it  causes  the  appetite 
to  rest,  as  it  were,  in  the  good  obtained :  and  this  belongs  to 
the  passion  of  delight  or  joy  :  the  contrary  of  which,  in  respect 
of  evil,  is  pain  or  sorrow. 

On  the  other  hand,  in  the  irascible  passions,  the  aptitude, 
or  inclination  to  seek  good,  or  to  shun  evil,  is  presupposed 
as  arising  from  the  concupiscible  faculty,  which  regards  good 
or  evil  absolutely.  And  in  respect  of  good  not  yet  obtained, 
we  have  hope  and  despair.  In  respect  of  evil  not  yet  present 
we  have  fear  and  daring.  But  in  respect  of  good  obtained 
there  is  no  irascible  passion:  because  it  is  no  longer  con- 
sidered in  the  light  of  something  arduous,  as  stated  above 
(A.  3).  But  evil  already  present  gives  rise  to  the  passion 
of  anger. 

Accordingly  it  is  clear  that  in  the  concupiscible  faculty 
there  are  three  couples  of  passions;  viz.,  love  and  hatred, 
desire  and  aversion,  joy  and  sadness.  In  like  manner  there 
are  three  couples  in  the  irascible  faculty;  viz.,  hope  and 
despair,  fear  and  daring,  and  anger  which  has  no  contrary 
passion. 

Consequently  there  are  altogether  eleven  passions  differ- 
ing specifically;  six  in  the  concupiscible  faculty,  and  five  in 
the  irascible;  and  under  these  all  the  passions  of  the  soul 
are  contained. 

From  this  the  replies  to  the  objections  are  evident. 


QUESTION  XXIV 

OF  GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  THE  PASSIONS  OF  THE  SOUL. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  good  and  evil  in  the  passions  of  the 
soul:  and  under  this  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  moral  good  and  evil  can  be  found  in  the  pas- 
sions of  the  soul  ?  (2)  Whether  every  passion  of  the  soul 
is  morally  evil  ?  (3)  Whether  every  passion  increases  or 
decreases  the  goodness  or  malice  of  an  act  ?  (4)  Whether 
any  passion  is  good  or  evil  specifically  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  moral  good  and  evil  can  be  found  in  the 
passions  of  the  soul  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  no  passion  of  the  soul  is  morally 
good  or  evil.  For  moral  good  and  evil  are  proper  to  man: 
since  morals  are  properly  predicated  of  man,  as  Ambrose  says 
(Super  Luc,  Prolog.).  But  passions  are  not  proper  to  man, 
for  he  has  them  in  common  with  other  animals.  Therefore 
no  passion  of  the  soul  is  morally  good  or  evil. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  good  or  evil  of  man  consists  in  being 
in  accord,  or  in  disaccord  with  reason,  as  Dionysius  says  (Div. 
Nom.  iv.).  Now  the  passions  of  the  soul  are  not  in  the 
reason,  but  in  the  sensitive  appetite,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXII. ,  A.  3).  Therefore  they  have  no  connection  with 
human,  i.e.,  moral,  good  or  evil. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  ii.)  that  we 
are  neither  praised  nor  blamed  for  our  passions.     But  we  are 

293 


294  ^      QUESTION  XXIV 

praised  and  blamed  for  moral  good  and  evil.  Therefore  the 
passions  are  not  morally  good  or  evil. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  while 
speaking  of  the  passions  of  the  soul :  They  are  evil  if  our  love 
is  evil ;  good  if  our  love  is  good. 

I  answer  that,  We  may  consider  the  passions  of  the  soul 
in  two  ways:  first,  in  themselves;  secondly,  as  being  subject 
to  the  command  of  the  reason  and  will. — -If  then  the  passions 
be  considered  in  themselves,  to  wit,  as  movements  of  the 
irrational  appetite,  thus  there  is  no  moral  good  or  evil  in 
them,  since  this  depends  on  the  reason,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XVIII. ,  A.  5).  If,  however,  they  be  considered  as  sub- 
ject to  the  command  of  the  reason  and  will,  then  moral  good 
and  evil  are  in  them.  Because  the  sensitive  appetite  is 
nearer  than  the  outward  members  to  the  reason  and  will; 
and  yet  the  movements  and  actions  of  the  outward  members 
are  morally  good  or  evil,  inasmuch  as  they  are  voluntary. 
Much  more,  therefore,  may  the  passions,  in  so  far  as  they  are 
voluntary,  be  called  morally  good  or  evil.  And  they  are 
said  to  be  voluntary,  either  from  being  commanded  by  the 
will,  or  from  not  being  checked  by  the  will. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  These  passions,  considered  in  themselves, 
are  common  to  man  and  other  animals :  but,  as  commanded 
by  the  reason,  they  are  proper  to  man. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Even  the  lower  appetitive  powers  are  called 
rational,  in  so  far  as  they  partake  of  reason  in  some  sort 
[Ethic,  i.). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  Philosopher  says  that  we  are  neither 
praised  nor  blamed  for  our  passions  considered  absolutely; 
but  he  does  not  exclude  their  becoming  worthy  of  praise  or 
blame,  in  so  far  as  they  are  subordinate  to  reason.  Hence 
he  continues :  For  the  man  who  fears  or  is  angry,  is  not  praised 
.  .  .  or  hlamed,  hut  the  man  who  is  angry  in  a  certain  way, 
i.e.,  according  to,  or  against  reason. 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  THE  PASSIONS  295 

Second  Article. 

whether  every  passion  of  the   soul  is  evil  morally  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — • 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  all  the  passions  of  the  soul  are 
morally  evil.  For  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  ix.)  that 
some  call  the  souVs  passions  diseases  or  disturbances  of  the 
soul.'^  But  every  disease  or  disturbance  of  the  soul  is  morally 
evil.     Therefore  every  passion  of  the  soul  is  evil  morally. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Damascene  says  {De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that 
movement  in  accord  with  nature  is  an  action,  but  movement 
contrary  to  nature  is  passion.  But  in  movements  of  the 
soul,  what  is  against  nature  is  sinful  and  morally  evil :  hence 
he  says  elsewhere  (ibid.)  that  the  devil  turned  from  that  which 
is  in  accord  with  nature  to  that  which  is  against  nature.  There- 
fore these  passions  are  morally  evil. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  whatever  leads  to  sin,  has  an  aspect  of 
evil.  But  these  passions  lead  to  sin:  wherefore  they  are 
called  the  passions  of  sins  (Rom.  vii.  5)..  Therefore  it  seems 
that  they  are  morally  evil. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  that 
all  these  emotions  are  right  in  those  whose  love  is  rightly  placed. 
.  .  .  For  they  fear  to  sin,  they  desire  to  persevere  ;  they  grieve 
for  sin,  they  rejoice  in  good  works. 

I  answer  that.  On  this  question  the  opinion  of  the  Stoics 
differed  from  that  of  the  Peripatetics:  for  the  Stoics  held 
that  all  passions  are  evil,  while  the  Peripatetics  maintained 
that  moderate  passions  are  good.  This  difference,  although 
It  appears  great  in  words,  is  nevertheless,  in  reality,  none  at 
all,  or  but  little,  if  we  consider  the  intent  of  either  school. 
For  the  Stoics  did  not  discern  between  sense  and  intellect; 
and  consequently  neither  between  the  intellectual  and  sen- 
sitive appetite.  Hence  neither  did  they  discriminate  the 
passions  of  the  soul  from  the  movements  of  the  will,  in  so 
far  as  the  passions  of  the  soul  are  in  the  sensitive  appetite, 
while  the  simple  movements  of  the  will  are  in  the  intellectual 

*  Cf.  Q.  XXIII.  A.  2,  footnote. 


296  QUESTION  XXIV 

appetite :  but  every  rational  movement  of  the  appetitive  part 
they  called  will,  while  they  called  passion,  a  movement  that 
exceeds  the  limits  of  reason.  Wherefore  Tully,  following 
their  opinion  (Tusc.  iii.)  calls  all  passions  diseases  of  the  soul  : 
whence  he  argues  that  those  who  are  diseased  are  unsound  ; 
and  that  those  who  are  unsound  are  wanting  in  sense.  Hence 
we  speak  of  those  who  are  wanting  in  sense  as  being  unsound. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  Peripatetics  give  the  name  of 
passions  to  all  the  movements  of  the  sensitive  appetite. 
Wherefore  they  esteem  them  good,  when  they  are  checked 
by  reason;  and  evil  when  they  are  unchecked  by  reason. 
Hence  it  is  evident  that  Tully  was  wrong  in  disapproving 
(ibid.)  of  the  Peripatetic  theory  of  a  mean  in  the  passions, 
when  he  says  that  every  evil,  though  moderate,  should  he 
shunned ;  for,  just  as  a  body,  though  it  be  moderately  ailing, 
is  not  sound ;  so,  this  mean  in  the  diseases  or  passions  of  the 
soul,  is  not  sound.  For  passions  are  not  called  diseases  or 
disturbances  of  the  soul,  save  when  they  are  unchecked  by 
reason. 

Hence  the  reply  to  the  First  Objection  is  evident. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  In  every  passion  there  is  an  increase  or  de- 
crease in  the  natural  movement  of  the  heart,  according  as 
the  heart  is  moved  more  or  less  intensely  by  contraction  and 
dilatation;  and  hence  it  derives  the  character  of  passion. 
But  there  is  no  need  for  passion  to  deviate  always  from  the 
order  of  natural  reason. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  passions  of  the  soul,  in  so  far  as  they  are 
contrary  to  the  order  of  reason,  incline  us  to  sin:  but  in  so 
far  as  they  are  controlled  by  reason,  they  pertain  to  virtue. 

Third  Article. 

whether  passion  increases  or  decreases  the  goodness 
or  malice  of  an  act  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  every  passion  decreases  the 
goodness  of  a  moral  action.  For  anything  that  hinders  the 
judgment  of  reason,  on  which  depends  the  goodness  of  a 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  THE  PASSIONS  297 

moral  act,  consequently  decreases  the  goodness  of  the  moral 
act.  But  every  passion  hinders  the  judgment  of  reason: 
for  Sallust  says  (CatiVn.)  :  All  those  that  take  counsel  about 
matters  of  doubt,  should  be  free  from  hatred,  anger,  friendship 
and  pity.  Therefore  passion  decreases  the  goodness  of  a 
moral  act. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  more  a  man's  action  is  like  to  God, 
the  better  it  is:  hence  the  Apostle  says  (Eph.  y.  t):  Be  ye 
followers  of  God,  as  most  dear  children.  But  God  and  the 
holy  angels  feel  no  anger  when  they  punish  .  .  .  no  fellow- 
feeling  with  misery  when  they  relieve  the  unhappy,  as  Augus- 
tine says  (De  Civ.  Dei  ix.).  Therefore  it  is  better  to  do  such- 
like deeds  without  than  with  a  passion  of  the  soul. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  just  as  moral  evil  depends  on  subordina- 
tion to  reason,  so  also  does  moral  good.  But  moral  evil  is 
lessened  by  passion :  for  he  sins  less,  who  sins  from  passion, 
than  he  who  sins  deliberately.  Therefore  he  does  a  better 
deed,  who  does  well  without  passion,  than  he  who  does  with 
passion. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Civ.  Dei  ix.)  that  the 
passion  of  pity  is  obedient  to  reason,  when  pity  is  bestowed 
without  violating  right,  as  when  the  poor  are  relieved,  or  the 
penitent  forgiven.  But  nothing  that  is  obedient  to  reason 
lessens  the  moral  good.  Therefore  a  passion  of  the  soul  does 
not  lessen  moral  good. 

/  answer  that.  As  the  Stoics  held  that  every  passion  of  the 
soul  is  evil,  they  consequently  held  that  every  passion  of 
the  soul  lessens  the  goodness  of  an  act ;  since  the  admixture 
of  evil  either  destroys  good  altogether,  or  makes  it  to  be  less 
good.  And  this  is  true  indeed,  if  by  passions  we  understand 
none  but  the  inordinate  movements  of  the  sensitive  appetite, 
considered  as  disturbances  or  ailments.  But  if  we  give  the 
name  of  passions  to  all  the  movements  of  the  sensitive  appe- 
tite, then  it  belongs  to  the  perfection  of  man's  good  that  his 
passions  be  moderated  by  reason.  For  since  man's  good 
is  founded  on  reason  as  its  root,  that  good  will  be  all  the 
more  perfect,  according  as  it  extends  to  more  things  per- 
taining to  man.     Wherefore  no  one  questions  the  fact  that 


298  QUESTION  XXIV 

it  belongs  to  the  perfection  of  moral  good,  that  the  actions 
of  the  outward  members  be  controlled  by  the  law  of  reason. 
Hence,  since  the  sensitive  appetite  can  obey  reason,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XVII.,  A.  7),  it  belongs  to  the  perfection  of  moral 
or  human  good,  that  the  passions  themselves  also  should  be 
controlled  by  reason. 

Accordingly  just  as  it  is  better  that  man  should  both 
will  good  and  do  it  in  his  external  act ;  so  also  does  it  belong 
to  the  perfection  of  moral  good,  that  man  should  be  moved 
unto  good,  not  only  in  respect  of  his  will,  but  also  in  respect 
of  his  sensitive  appetite;  according  to  Ps.  Ixxxiii.  3:  My 
heart  and  my  flesh  have  rejoiced  in  the  living  God  :  where  by 
heart  we  are  to  understand  the  intellectual  appetite,  and  by 
■flesh  the  sensitive  appetite. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  passions  of  the  soul  may  stand  in  a  two- 
fold relation  to  the  judgment  of  reason.  First,  antecedently : 
and  thus,  because  they  obscure  the  judgment  of  reason, 
on  which  the  goodness  of  the  moral  act  depends,  they 
diminish  the  goodness  of  the  act ;  for  it  is  more  praiseworthy 
to  do  a  work  of  charity  from  the  judgment  of  reason  than 
from  the  mere  passion  of  pity. — In  the  second  place,  con- 
sequently: and  this  in  two  ways.  First,  by  way  of  redun- 
dance: because,  to  wit,  when  the  higher  part  of  the  soul  is 
intensely  moved  to  anything,  the  lower  part  also  follows 
that  movement ;  and  thus  the  passion  that  results  in  conse- 
quence, is  a  sign  of  the  intensity  of  the  will,  and  so  indicates 
greater  moral  goodness. — Secondly,  by  way  of  choice;  when, 
to  wit,  a  man,  by  the  judgment  of  his  reason,  chooses  to  be 
affected  by  a  passion  in  order  to  work  more  promptly 
with  the  co-operation  of  the  sensitive  appetite.  And 
thus  a  passion  of  the  soul  increases  the  goodness  of  an 
action. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  In  God  and  the  angels  there  is  no  sensitive 
appetite,  nor  again  bodily  members:  and  so  in  them  good 
does  not  depend  on  the  right  ordering  of  passions  or  of 
bodily  actions,  as  it  does  in  us. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  A  passion  that  tends  to  evil,  and  precedes 
the  judgment  of  reason,  diminishes  sin;  but  if  it  be  conse- 


GOOD  AND  EVIL  IN  THE  PASSIONS  299 

quent  in  either  of  the  ways  meDtioned  above  (Reply  Ohj.  i), 
it  aggravates  the  sin,  or  else  it  is  a  sign  of  its  being  more 
grievous. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  any  passion  is  good  or  evil  in  its 

SPECIES  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  no  passion  of  the  soul  is  morally 
good  or  evil  according  to  its  species.  Because  moral  good 
and  evil  depend  on  reason.  But  the  passions  are  in  the 
sensitive  appetite;  so  that  accordance  with  reason  is  acci- 
dental to  them.  Since,  therefore,  nothing  accidental 
belongs  to  a  thing's  species,  it  seems  that  no  passion  is  good 
or  evil  according  to  its  species. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  acts  and  passions  take  their  species  from 
their  object.  If,  therefore,  any  passion  were  good  or  evil 
according  to  its  species,  it  would  follow  that  those  passions, 
the  object  of  which  is  good,  are  specifically  good,  such  as 
love,  desire  and  joy:  and  that  those  passions,  the  object  of 
which  is  evil,  are  specifically  evil  as  hatred,  fear  and 
sadness.  But  this  is  clearly  false.  Therefore  no  passion 
is  good  or  evil  according  to  its  species. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  there  is  no  species  of  passion  that  is  not 
to  be  found  in  other  animals.  But  moral  good  is  in  man 
alone.  Therefore  no  passion  of  the  soul  is  good  or  evil 
according  to  its  species. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [De  Civ.  Dei  ix.)  that 
pity  is  a  kind  of  virtue.  Moreover,  the  Philosopher  says 
(Ethic,  ii.)  that  bashfulness  is  a  praiseworthy  passion. 
Therefore  some  passions  are  good  or  evil  according  to  their 
species. 

/  answer  that,  We  ought;  seemingly,  to  apply  to  passions 
what  has  been  said  in  regard  to  acts  (Q.  XVIII.,  AA.  5,  6; 
Q.  XX.,  A.  i) — viz.,  that  the  species  of  a  passion,  as  the 
species  of  an  act,  can  be  considered  from  two  points  of  view. 
First,  according  to  its  natural  genus;  and  thus  moral  good 
and  evil  have  no  connection  with  the  species  of  an  act  or 


300  QUESTION  XXIV 

passion.  Secondly,  according  to  its  moral  genus,  inasmuch 
as  it  is  voluntary  and  controlled  by  reason.  In  this  way 
moral  good  and  evil  can  belong  to  the  species  of  a  passion, 
in  so  far  as  the  object  to  which  a  passion  tends,  is,  of  itself, 
in  harmony  or  in  discord  with  reason :  as  is  clear  in  the  case 
of  shame  which  is  base  fear ;  and  of  envy  which  is  sorrow  for 
another's  good :  for  thus  passions  belong  to  the  same  species 
as  the  external  act. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  This  argument  considers  the  passions  in 
their  natural  species,  in  so  far  as  the  sensitive  appetite  is 
considered  in  itself.  But  in  so  far  as  the  sensitive  appetite 
obeys  reason,  good  and  evil  of  reason  are  no  longer  accident- 
ally in  the  passions  of  the  appetite,  but  essentially. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Passions  having  a  tendency  to  good,  are 
themselves  good,  if  they  tend  to  that  which  is  truly  good, 
and  in  like  manner,  if  they  turn  away  from  that  which  is 
truly  evil.  On  the  other  hand,  those  passions  which  consist 
in  aversion  from  good,  and  a  tendency  to  evil,  are  themselves 

evil. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  irrational  animals  the  sensitive  appetite 
does  not  obey  reason.  Nevertheless,  in  so  far  as  they  are 
led  by  a  kind  of  estimative  power,  which  is  subject  to  a 
higher,  i.e.,  the  Divine,  reason,  there  is  a  certain  likeness  of 
moral  good  in  them,  in  regard  to  the  soul's  passions. 


QUESTION  XXV. 

OF  THE  ORDER  OF  THE  PASSIONS  TO  ONE  ANOTHER. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  order  of  the  jpassions  to  one 
another :  and  under  this  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry : 
(i)  The  order  of  the  irascible  passions  in  comparison  with 
the  concupiscible  passions.  (2)  The  order  of  the  con- 
cupiscible  passions  among  themselves.  (3)  The  order  of 
the  irascible  passions  among  themselves.  (4)  The  four 
principal  passions. 

First  Article. 

whether  the  irascible  passions  precede  the  concu- 
piscible passions,  or  vice  versa  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  irascible  passions  precede 
the  concupiscible  passions.  For  the  order  of  the  passions 
is  that  of  their  objects.  But  the  object  of  the  irascible 
faculty  is  the  difficult  good,  which  seems  to  be  the  highest 
good.  Therefore  the  irascible  passions  seem  to  precede  the 
concupiscible  passions. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  mover  precedes  that  which  is  moved. 

But  the  irascible  faculty  is  compared  to  the  concupiscible, 

as  mover  to  that  which  is  moved :  since  it  is  given  to  animals, 

for  the  purpose  of  removing  the  obstacles  that  hinder  the 

concupiscible  faculty  from  enjoying  its  object,  as  stated 

above  (Q.  XXIII.,  A.  1  ad  t\    P.  i,    Q.   LXXXI.,   A.  2). 

Now  that  which  removes  an   obstacle,   is  a  kind  of  mover 

(Phys.  viii.).     Therefore  the  irascible  passions  precede  the 

concupiscible  passions. 

301 


302  QUESTION  XXV 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  joy  and  sadness  are  concupiscible 
passions.  But  joy  and  sadness  succeed  to  the  irascible 
passions:  for  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.)  that  retalia- 
tion causes  anger  to  cease,  because  it  produces  pleasure  instead 
of  the  previous  pain.  Therefore  the  concupiscible  passions 
follow  the  irascible  passions. 

On  the  contrary,  The  concupiscible  passions  regard  the 
absolute  good,  while  the  irascible  passions  regard  a  restricted, 
viz.,  the  difhcult,  good.  Since,  therefore,  the  absolute  good 
precedes  the  restricted  good,  it  seems  that  the  concupiscible 
passions  precede  the  irascible. 

/  answer  that.  In  the  concupiscible  passions  there  is  more 
diversity  than  in  the  passions  of  the  irascible  faculty.  For 
in  the  former  we  find  something  relating  to  movement — • 
e.g.,  desire;  and  something  belonging  to  repose,  e.g.,  joy  and 
sadness.  But  in  the  irascible  passions  there  is  nothing 
pertaining  to  repose,  and  only  that  which  belongs  to  move- 
ment. The  reason  of  this  is  that  when  we  find  rest  in  a 
thing,  we  no  longer  look  upon  it  as  something  difficult 
or  arduous;  whereas  such  is  the  object  of  the  irascible 
faculty. 

Now  since  rest  is  the  end  of  movement,  it  is  first  in  the 
order  of  intention,  but  last  in  the  order  of  execution.  If, 
therefore,  we  compare  the  passions  of  the  irascible  faculty 
to  those  concupiscible  passions  that  denote  rest  in  good, 
it  is  evident  that  in  the  order  of  execution,  the  irascible 
passions  take  precedence  of  suchlike  passions  of  the  con- 
cupiscible faculty:  thus  hope  precedes  joy,  and  hence  causes 
it,  according  to  the  Apostle  (Rom.  xii.  12):  Rejoicing  in 
hope.  But  the  concupiscible  passion  which  denotes  rest 
in  evil,  viz.,  sadness,  comes  between  two  irascible  passions: 
because  it  follows  fear;  since  we  become  sad  when  we  are 
confronted  by  the  evil  that  we  feared:  while  it  precedes 
the  movement  of  anger ;  since  the  movement  of  self-vindica- 
tion, that  results  from  sadness,  is  the  movement  of  anger. 
And  because  it  is  looked  upon  as  a  good  thing  to  pay  back 
the  evil  done  to  us;  when  the  angry  man  has  achieved  this 
he  rejoices.      Thus  it  is  evident  that  every  passion  of  the 


ORDER  OF  PASSIONS  TO  ONE  ANOTHER      303 

irascible  faculty  terminates  in  a  concupiscible  passion 
denoting  rest,  viz.,  either  in  joy  or  in  sadness. 

But  if  we  compare  the  irascible  passions  to  those  con- 
cupiscible passions  that  denote  movement,  then  it  is  clear 
that  the  latter  take  precedence:  because  the  passions  of 
the  irascible  faculty  add  something  to  those  of  the  con- 
cupiscible faculty;  just  as  the  object  of  the  irascible  adds 
the  aspect  of  arduousness  or  difficulty  to  the  object  of  the 
concupiscible  faculty.  Thus  hope  adds  to  desire,  a  certain 
effort,  and  a  certain  raising  of  the  spirits  to  the  realization 
of  the  arduous  good.  In  like  manner  fear  adds  to  aversion 
or  detestation,  a  certain  lowness  of  spirits,  on  account  of 
difficulty  in  shunning  the  evil. 

Accordingly  the  passions  of  the  irascible  faculty  stand 
between  those  concupiscible  passions  that  denote  move* 
ment  towards  good  or  evil,  and  those  concupiscible  passions 
that  denote  rest  in  good  or  evil.  And  it  is  therefore  evident 
that  the  irascible  passions  both  arise  from  and  terminate 
in  the  passions  of  the  concupiscible  faculty. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  argument  would  prove,  if  the  formal 
object  of  the  concupiscible  faculty  were  something  con- 
trary to  the  arduous,  just  as  the  formal  object  of  the 
irascible  faculty  is  that  which  is  arduous.  But  because  the 
object  of  the  concupiscible  faculty  is  good  absolutely,  it 
naturally  precedes  the  object  of  the  irascible,  as  the  common 
precedes  the  proper. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  remover  of  an  obstacle  is  not  a  direct 
but  an  accidental  mover :  and  here  we  are  speaking  of  passions 
as  directly  ordered  to  one  another. — -Moreover,  the  irascible 
passion  removes  the  obstacle  that  hinders  the  concupiscible 
from  resting  in  its  object.  Wherefore  it  only  follows  that 
the  irascible  passions  precede  those  concupiscible  passions 
that  denote  rest. — The  third  objection  leads  to  the  same 
conclusion. 


304  QUESTION  XXV 


Second  Article. 

whether  love  is  the  first  of  the  concupiscible 

passions  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  love  is  not  the  first  of  the 
concupiscible  passions.  For  the  concupiscible  faculty  is 
so  called  from  concupiscence,  which  is  the  same  passion 
as  desire.  But  names  are  taken  from  that  which  predominates 
(De  Anima  ii.).     Therefore  desire  takes  precedence  of  love. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  love  implies  a  certain  union;  since  it  is 
a  uniting  and  binding  force,  as  Dionysius  states  (Div.  Nom. 
iv,).  But  concupiscence  or  desire  is  a  movement  towards 
union  with  the  thing  coveted  or  desired.  Therefore  desire 
precedes  love. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  cause  precedes  its  effect.  But 
pleasure  is  sometimes  th  e  cause  of  love :  since  some  love  for 
the  sake  of  pleasure  (Ethic,  viii.).  Therefore  pleasure 
precedes  love;  and  consequently  love  is  not  the  first  of  the 
passions. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  that 
all  the  passions  are  caused  by  love :  since  love  yearning  for  the 
beloved  object,  is  desire  ;  and,  having  and  enjoying  it,  is  joy. 
Therefore  love  is  the  first  of  the  concupiscible  passions. 

/  answer  that,  Good  and  evil  are  the  objects  of  the  con- 
cupiscible faculty.  Now  good  naturally  precedes  evil; 
since  evil  is  the  privation  of  good.  Wherefore  all  the 
passions,  the  object  of  which  is  good,  are  naturally  before 
those,  the  object  of  which  is  evil, — that  is  to  say,  each  pre- 
cedes its  contrary  passion:  because  the  quest  of  a  good  is 
the  reason  for  shunning  the  opposite  evil. 

Now  good  has  the  aspect  of  an  end,  and  the  end  is  indeed 
first  in  the  order  of  intention,  but  last  in  the  order  of  execu- 
tion. Consequently  the  order  of  the  concupiscible  passions 
can  be  considered  either  in  the  order  of  intention  or  in  the 
order  of  execution.  In  the  order  of  execution,  the  first 
place  belongs  to  that  which  takes  place  first  in  the  thing 


ORDER  OF  PASSIONS  TO  ONE  ANOTHER      305 

that  tends  to  the  end.  Now  it  is  evident  that  whatever 
tends  to  an  end,  has,  in  the  first  place,  an  aptitude  or  pro- 
portion to  that  end,  for  nothing  tends  to  a  disproportionate 
end;  secondly,  it  is  moved  to  that  end;  thirdly,  it  rests  in 
the  end,  after  having  attained  it.  And  this  very  aptitude 
or  proportion  of  the  appetite  to  good  is  love,  which  is 
complacency  in  good;  while  movement  towards  good  is 
desire  or  concupiscence;  and  rest  in  good  is  joy  or  pleasure. 
Accordingly  in  this  order,  love  precedes  desire,  and  desire 
precedes  pleasure. — But  in  the  order  of  intention,  it  is  the 
reverse:  because  the  pleasure  intended  causes  desire  and 
love.  For  pleasure  is  the  enjoyment  of  the  good,  which 
enjoyment  is,  in  a  way,  the  end,  just  as  the  good  itself  is, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XI.,  A.  3  ad  ^). 

Reply  Ob]',  i.  We  name  a  thing  as  we  understand  it,  for 
words  are  signs  of  thoughts,  as  the  Philosopher  states  {Peri 
Herm.  i.).  Now  in  most  cases  we  know  a  cause  by  its  effect. 
But  the  effect  of  love,  when  the  beloved  object  is  possessed, 
is  pleasure:  when  it  is  not  possessed,  it  is  desire  or  concu- 
piscence: and,  as  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  x.),  we  are 
more  sensible  to  love,  when  we  lack  that  which  we  love.  Con- 
sequently of  all  the  concupiscible  passions,  concupiscence 
is  felt  most;  and  for  this  reason  the  power  is  named  after  it. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  union  of  lover  and  beloved  is  twofold. 
There  is  real  union,  consisting  in  the  conjunction  of  one 
with  the  other.  This  union  belongs  to  joy  or  pleasure, 
which  follows  desire.  There  is  also  an  affective  union, 
consisting  in  an  aptitude  or  proportion,  in  so  far  as  one 
thing,  from  the  very  fact  of  its  having  an  aptitude  for  and 
an  inclination  to  another,  partakes  of  it :  and  love  betokens 
such  a  union.  This  union  precedes  the  movement  of 
desire. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Pleasure  causes  love,  in  so  far  as  it  precedes 
love  in  the  order  of  intention. 


II.  I  20 


3o6  QUESTION  XXV 


Third  Article. 

whether  hope  is  the  first  of  the  irascible 

passions  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  hope  is  not  the  first  of  the 
irascible  passions.  Because  the  irascible  faculty  is  de- 
nominated from  anger.  Since,  therefore,  names  are  taken 
from  that  which  predominates  (cf.  A.  2,  Obj.  i),  it  seems 
that  anger  precedes  and  surpasses  hope. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  object  of  the  irascible  faculty  is 
something  arduous.  Now  it  seems  more  arduous  to  strive 
to  overcome  a  contrary  evil  that  threatens  soon  to  over- 
take us,  which  pertains  to  daring;  or  an  evil  actually  present, 
which  pertains  to  anger;  than  to  strive  simply  to  obtain 
some  good.  Again,  it  seems  more  arduous  to  strive  to 
overcome  a  present  evil,  than  a  future  evil.  Therefore 
anger  seems  to  be  a  stronger  passion  than  daring,  and 
daring,  than  hope.  And  consequently  it  seems  that  hope 
should  not  precede  them. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  when  a  thing  is  moved  towards  an  end, 
the  movement  of  withdrawal  precedes  the  movement  of 
approach.  But  fear  and  despair  imply  withdrawal  from 
something;  while  daring  and  hope  imply  approach  towards 
something:  Therefore  fear  and  despair  precede  hope  and 
daring. 

On  the  contrary,  The  nearer  a  thing  is  to  the  first,  the  more 
it  precedes  others.  But  hope  is  nearer  to  love,  which  is 
the  first  of  the  passions.  Therefore  hope  is  the  first  of  the 
passions  in  the  irascible  faculty. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i)  all  the  irascible 
passions  denote  movement  towards  something.  Now  this 
movement  of  the  irascible  faculty  towards  something  is 
due  to  one  of  two  causes :  one  is  the  mere  aptitude  or  pro- 
portion to  the  end;  and  this  pertains  to  love  or  hatred; 
the  other  is  the  presence  of  good  or  evil;  and  this  belongs 
to  sadness  or  joy.     As  a  matter  of  fact,  the  presence  of  good 


ORDER  OF  PASSIONS  TO  ONE  ANOTHER      307 

produces  no  passion  in  the  irascible,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXIII.,  AA.  3,  4);  but  the  presence  of  evil  gives  rise 
to  the  passion  of  anger. 

Since  then  in  the  order  of  generation  or  execution,  pro- 
portion or  aptitude  to  the  end  precedes  the  achievement 
of  the  end;  it  follows  that,  of  all  the  irascible  passions, 
anger  is  the  last  in  the  order  of  generation.  And  among 
the  other  passions  of  the  irascible  faculty,  which  denote  a 
movement  arising  from  love  of  good  or  hatred  of  evil, 
those  whose  object  is  good,  viz.,  hope  and  despair,  must 
needs  naturally  precede  those  whose  object  is  evil,  viz., 
daring  and  fear:  yet  so  that  hope  precedes  despair;  since 
hope  is  a  movement  towards  good  as  such,  which  is  essen- 
tially attractive,  so  that  hope  tends  to  good  directly; 
whereas  despair  is  a  movement  away  from  good,  a  move- 
ment which  is  consistent  with  good,  not  as  such,  but  in 
respect  of  something  else,  wherefore  its  tendency  from  good 
is  accidental,  as  it  were.  In  like  manner  fear,  through 
being  a  movement  from  evil,  precedes  daring. — And  that 
hope  and  despair  naturally  precede  fear  and  daring  is  evident 
from  this, — that  as  the  desire  of  good  is  the  reason  for 
avoiding  evil,  so  hope  and  despair  are  the  reason  for  fear 
and  daring :  because  daring  arises  from  the  hope  of  victory, 
and  fear  arises  from  the  despair  of  overcoming.  Lastly, 
anger  arises  from  daring :  for  no  one  is  angry  while  seeking 
vengeance,  unless  he  dare  to  avenge  himself,  as  Avicenna 
observes  in  his  Physics  (De  Anima  iv.).  Accordingly, 
it  is  evident  that  hope  is  the  first  of  all  the  irascible 
passions. 

And  if  we  wish  to  know  the  order  of  all  the  passions  in 
the  way  of  generation,  love  and  hatred  are  first ;  desire  and 
aversion,  second;  hope  and  despair,  third;  fear  and  daring, 
fourth;  anger,  fifth;  sixth  and  last,  joy  and  sadness,  which 
follow  from  all  the  passions,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  ii. :  yet  so 
that  love  precedes  hatred;  desire  precedes  aversion;  hope 
precedes  despair;  fear  precedes  daring;  and  joy  precedes 
sadness,  as  may  be  gathered  from  what  has  been  stated 
above  {cf.  this  and  preceding  articles). 


3o8  QUESTION  XXV 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  It  is  because  anger  arises  from  the  other 
passions,  as  an  effect  from  the  causes  that  precede  it,  that 
the  power  takes  its  name  from  anger  as  being  more  manifest 
than  the  other  passions. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  It  is  not  the  arduousness  but  the  good  that 
is  the  reason  for  approach  or  desire.  Consequently  hope, 
which  regards  good  more  directly,  takes  precedence: 
although  at  times  daring  or  even  anger  regards  something 
more  arduous. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  movement  of  the  appetite  is  essentially 
and  directly  towards  the  good;  its  movement  from  evil 
results  from  this.  For  the  movement  of  the  appetitive 
part  is  in  proportion  not  to  natural  movement,  but  to  the 
intention  of  nature,  which  intends  the  end  before  intending 
the  removal  of  a  contrary,  which  removal  is  desired  only  for 
the  sake  of  obtaining  the  end. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  these  are  the  four  principal  passions,— joy, 
sadness,  hope,  and  fear  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  joy,  sadness,  hope  and  fear 
are  not  the  four  principal  passions.  For  Augustine  {De 
Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  omits  hope  and  puts  desire  in  its  place. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  there  is  a  twofold  order  in  the  passions 
of  the  soul:  the  order  of  intention,  and  the  order  of  execu- 
tion or  generation.  The  principal  passions  should  therefore 
be  taken,  either  in  the  order  of  intention;  and  thus  joy  and 
sadness,  which  are  the  final  passions,  will  be  the  principal 
passions;  or  in  the  order  of  execution  or  generation;  and 
thus  love  will  be  the  principal  passion.  Therefore  joy  and 
sadness,  hope  and  fear  should  in  no  way  be  called  the  four 
principal  passions. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  just  as  daring  is  caused  by  hope,  so  fear 
is  caused  by  despair.  Either,  therefore,  hope  and  despair, 
should  be  reckoned  as  principal  passions,  since  they  cause 
others :  or  hope  and  daring,  from  being  akin  to  one  another. 


ORDER  OF  PASSIONS  TO  ONE  ANOTHER      309 

On  the  contrary,  Boethius  {De  Consol.  i.)  in  enumerating 
the  four  principal  passions,  says : 

Banish  joys:  banish  fears: 

Away  with  hope :  away  with  tears. 

/  answer  that,  These  four  are  commonly  called  the  princi- 
pal passions.  Two  of  them,  viz.,  joy  and  sadness,  are  said 
to  be  principal,  because  in  them  all  the  other  passions  have 
their  completion  and  end;  wherefore  they  arise  from  all 
the  other  passions,  as  is  stated  in  Ethic,  ii. — Fear  and  hope 
are  principal  passions,  not  because  they  complete  the  others 
simply,  but  because  they  complete  them  as  regards  the 
movement  of  the  appetite  towards  something :  for  in  respect 
of  good,  movement  begins  in  love,  goes  forward  to  desire, 
and  ends  in  hope ;  while  in  respect  of  evil,  it  begins  in  hatred, 
goes  on  to  aversion,  and  ends  in  fear. — Hence  it  is  customary 
to  distinguish  these  four  passions  in  relation  to  the  present 
and  the  future :  for  movement  regards  the  future,  while  rest 
is  in  something  present:  so  that  joy  relates  to  present  good; 
sadness  relates  to  present  evil;  hope  regards  future  good, 
and  fear,  future  evil. 

As  to  the  other  passions  that  regard  good  or  evil,  present 
or  future,  they  all  culminate  in  these  four.  For  this 
reason  some  have  said  that  these  four  are  the  principal 
passions,  because  they  are  general  passions:  and  this  is 
true,  provided  that  by  hope  and  fear  we  understand  the 
common  tendency  of  the  appetite  to  desire  or  aversion  for 
something. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Augustine  puts  desire  or  covetousness  in 
place  of  hope,  in  so  far  as  they  seem  to  regard  the  same 
object,  viz.,  some  future  good. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  These  are  called  principal  passions,  in  the 
order  of  intention  and  completion.  And  though  fear  and 
hope  are  not  the  last  passions  simply,  yet  they  are  the  last 
of  those  passions  that  tend  towards  something  as  future- 
Nor  can  the  argument  be  pressed  any  further  except  in 
the  case  of  anger:  yet  neither  can  anger  be  reckoned  a 
principal  passion,  because  it  is  an  effect  of  daring,  which 


310  QUESTION  XXV 

cannot  be  a  principal  passion,  as  we  shall  state  further  on 
(Reply  Ohj.  3). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Despair  implies  movement  away  from 
good;  and  this  is,  as  it  were,  accidental:  and  daring  implies 
movement  towards  evil;  and  this  too  is  accidental.  Con- 
sequently these  cannot  be  principal  passions;  because  that 
which  is  accidental  cannot  be  said  to  be  principal.  And  so 
neither  can  anger  be  called  a  principal  passion,  because  it 
arises  from  daring. 


QUESTION  XKVI. 

OF  THE  PASSIONS  OF  THE  SOUL  IN  PARTICULAR, 
AND  FIRST,   OF  LOVE. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  have  now  to  consider  the  soul's  passions  in  particular, 
and  (i)  the  passions  of  the  concupiscible  faculty;  (2)  the 
passions  of  the  irascible  faculty. 

The  first  of  these  considerations  will  be  threefold;  since 
we  shall  consider  (i)  Love  and  hatred;  (2)  Desire  and 
aversion;  (3)  Pleasure  and  sadness. 

Concerning  love,  three  points  must  be  considered :  (i)  Love 
itself;  (2)  The  cause  of  love;  (3)  The  effects  of  love.  Under 
the  first  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether 
love  is  in  the  concupiscible  power  ?  (2)  Whether  love,  is  a 
passion  ?  (3)  Whether  love  is  the  same  as  dilection  ? 
(4)  Whether  love  is  properly  divided  into  love  of  friendship, 
and  love  of  concupiscence  ? 

First  Article  ? 
whether  love  is  in  the  concupiscible  power  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  love  is  not  in  the  concupiscible 
power.  For  it  is  written  (Wis.  viii.  2) :  Her,  namely,  wisdom, 
have  I  loved,  and  have  sought  her  out  from  my  youth.  But 
the  concupiscible  power,  being  a  part  of  the  sensitive  appe- 
tite, cannot  tend  to  wisdom,  which  is  not  apprehended  by 
the  senses.     Therefore  love  is  not  in  the  concupiscible  power. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  love  seems  to  be  identified  with  every 
passion:  for  x\ugustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.):  Love,  yearn- 

311 


312  QUESTION  XXVI 

ing  for  the  object  beloved,  is  desire  ;  having  and  enjoying  it, 
is  joy  ;  fleeing  what  is  contrary  to  it,  is  fear  ;  and  feeling 
what  is  contrary  to  it,  is  sadness.  But  not  every  passion  is 
in  the  concupiscible  power ;  indeed,  fear,  which  is  mentioned 
in  this  passage,  is  in  the  irascible  power.  Therefore  we 
must  not  say  absolutely  that  love  is  in  the  concupiscible 
power. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Dionysius  {Div.  Nom.  iv.)  mentions  a 
natural  love.  But  natural  love  seems  to  pertain  rather  to 
the  natural  powers,  that  belong  to  the  vegetal  soul.  There- 
fore love  is  not  simply  in  the  concupiscible  power. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Topic,  ii.)  that 
love  is  in  the  concupiscible  power. 

I  answer  that.  Love  is  something  pertaining  to  the  appe- 
tite; since  good  is  the  object  of  both.  Wherefore  love  differs 
according  to  the  difference  of  appetites.  For  there  is  an 
appetite  which  arises,  from  an  apprehension  existing,  not 
in  the  subject  of  the  appetite,  but  in  some  other: 
and  this  is  called  the  natural  appetite.  Because  natural 
things  seek  what  is  suitable  to  them  according  to  their 
nature,  by  reason  of  an  apprehension  which  is  not  in  them, 
but  in  the  Author  of  their  nature,  as  stated  in  the  First 
Fart  (Q.  VL,  k.  1.  ad  2\Q.  CIIL,  A.  i  ad  i,  3).— And  there 
is  another  appetite  arising  from  an  apprehension  in  the 
subject  of  the  appetite,  but  from  necessity  and  not  from 
free-will.  Such  is,  in  irrational  animals,  the  sensitive 
appetite,  which,  however,  in  man,  has  a  certain  share  of 
liberty,  in  so  far  as  it  obeys  reason. — Again,  there  is  another 
appetite  following  freely  from  an  apprehension  in  the  subject 
of  the  appetite.  And  this  is  the  rational  or  intellectual 
appetite,  which  is  called  the  will. 

Now  in  each  of  these  appetites,  the  name  love  is  given  to 
the  principle  of  movement  towards  the  end  loved.  In  the 
natural  appetite  the  principle  of  this  movement  is  the 
appetitive  subject's  connaturalhess  with  the  thing  to  which 
it  tends,  and  may  be  called  natural  love  :  thus  the  connatur- 
alness  of  a  heavy  body  for  the  centre,  is  by  reason  of  its  weight 
and  may  be  called  natural  love.     In  like  manner  the  aptitude 


LOVE,  IN  ITSELF  313 

of  the  sensitive  appetite  or  of  the  will  to  some  good;  that 
is  to  say,  its  very  complacency  in  good,  is  called  sensi- 
tive love,  or  intellectual  or  rational  love.  So  that  sensitive 
love  is  in  the  sensitive  appetite,  just  as  intellectual  love  is 
in  the  intellectual  appetite.  And  it  belongs  to  the  concu- 
piscible  power,  because  it  regards  good  absolutely,  and  not 
under  the  aspect  of  difficulty,  which  is  the  object  of  the 
irascible  faculty. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  w^ords  quoted  refer  to  intellectual  or 
rational  love. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Love  is  spoken  of  as  being  fear,  joy,  desire 
and  sadness,  not  essentially  but  causally. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Natural  love  is  not  only  in  the  powers  of 
the  vegetal  soul,  but  also  in  all  the  soul's  powers,  and  all 
the  parts  of  the  bod}^  and  universally  in  all  things :  because, 
as  Dionysius  says  {Div.  Horn,  iv.).  Beauty  and  goodness,  are 
beloved  by  all  things  ;  since  each  single  thing  has  a  con- 
naturalness  with  that  which  is  naturally  suitable  to  it. 

Second  Article, 
whether  love  is  a  passion  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  :  — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  love  is  not  a  passion.  For 
no  power  is  a  passion.  But  every  love  is  a  power,  as  Diony- 
sius says  [Div.  Nom.  iv.).      Therefore  love  is  not  a  passion. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  love  is  a  kind  of  union  or  bond,  as 
Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  viii.).  But  a  union  or  bond  is 
not  a  passion,  but  rather  a  relation.  Therefore  love  is  not 
a  passion. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.) 
that  passion  is  a  movement.  But  love  does  not  imply  the 
movement  of  the  appetite;  for  this  is  desire,  of  which  move- 
ment love  is  the  principle.     Therefore  love  is  not  a  passion. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  viii.)  that 
love  is  a  passion. 

I  answer  that.  Passion  is  the  effect  of  the  agent  on  the 
patient.     Now  a  natural  agent  produces  a  twofold  effect 


314  QUESTION  XXVI 

on  the  patient:  for  in  the  first  place  it  gives  it  the  form; 
and  secondly  it  gives  it  the  movement  that  results  from 
the  form.  Thus  the  generator  gives  the  generated  body 
both  weight  and  the  movement  resulting  from  weight:  so 
that  weight,  from  being  the  principle  of  movement  to  the 
place,  which  is  connatural  to  that  body  by  reason  of  its 
weight,  can,  in  a  way,  be  called  natural  love.  In  the  same 
way  the  appetible  object  gives  the  appetite,  first,  a  certain 
adaptation  to  itself,  which  consists  in  complacency  in  that 
object;  and  from  this  follows  movement  towards  the  appet- 
ible object.  For  the  appetitive  movement  is  ciycular,  as 
stated  in  De  Anima  iii. ;  because  the  appetible  object  moves 
the  appetite,  introducing  itself,  as  it  were,  to  its  intention ; 
while  the  appetite  moves  towards  the  realization  of  the 
appetible  object,  so  that  the  movement  ends  where  it  began. 
Accordingly,  the  first  change  wrought  in  the  appetite  by 
the  appetible  object  is  called  love,  and  is  nothing  else  than 
complacency  in  that  object;  and  from  this  complacency 
results  a  movement  towards  that  same  object,  and  this 
movement  is  desire  ;  and  lastly,  there  is  rest  which  is  joy. 
Since,  therefore,  love  consists  in  a  change  wrought  in  the 
appetite  by  the  appetible  object,  it  is  evident  that  love  is 
a  passion:  properly  so  called,  according  as  it  is  in  the  con- 
cupiscible  faculty ;  in  a  wider  and  extended  sense,  according 
as  it  is  in  the  will. 

Reply  Ob],  i.  Since  power  denotes  a  principle  of  move- 
ment or  action,  Dionysius  calls  love  a  power,  in  so  far  as  it 
is  a  principle  of  movement  in  the  appetite. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Union  belongs  to  love  in  so  far  as  by  reason 
of  the  complacency  of  the  appetite,  the  lover  stands  in 
relation  to  that  which  he  loves,  as  though  it  were  himself 
or  part  of  himself.  Hence  it  is  clear  that  love  is  not  the  very 
relation  of  union,  but  that  union  is  a  result  of  love.  Hence, 
too,  Dionysius  says  that  love  is  a  unitive force  {Div.  Norn,  iv.), 
and  the  Philosopher  says  (Polit.  ii.)  that  union  is  the  work 
of  love. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Although  love  does  not  denote  the  move- 
ment of  the  appetite  in  tending  towards  the  appetible  object. 


LOVE.  IN  ITSELF  3i5 

yet  it  denotes  that  movement  whereby  the  appetite  is 
changed  by  the  appetible  object,  so  as  to  have  complacency 
therein. 

Third  Article, 
whether  love  is  the  same  as  dilection  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  love  is  the  same  as  dilection. 
For  Dionysius  says  {Div.  Nom.  iv.)  that  love  is  to  dilection, 
as  four  is  to  twice  two,  and  as  a  rectilinear  figure  is  to  one 
composed  of  straight  lines.  But  these  have  the  same  meaning. 
Therefore  love  and  dilection  denote  the  same  thing. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  movements  of  the  appetite  differ 
by  reason  of  their  objects.  But  the  objects  of  dilection 
and  love  are  the  same.     Therefore  these  are  the  same. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  dilection  and  love  differ,  it  seems  that 
it  is  chiefly  in  the  fact  that  dilection  refers  to  good  things, 
love  to  evil  things,  as  some  have  maintained,  according  to 
Augustine  (De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.).  But  they  do  not  differ  thus; 
because  as  Augustine  says  [ibid.)  the  holy  Scripture  uses 
both  words  in  reference  to  either  good  or  bad  things.  There- 
fore love  and  dilection  do  not  differ :  thus  indeed  Augustine 
concludes  {ibid.)  that  it  is  not  one  thing  to  speak  of  love,  and 
another  to  speak  of  dilection. 

On  the  contrary,  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Nom.  iv.)  that  some 
holy  men  have  held  that  love  means  something  more  Godlike 
than  dilection  does. 

I  answer  that,  We  find  four  words  referring,  in  a  way,  to 
the  same  thing:  viz.,  love,  dilection,  charity  and  friendship. 
They  differ,  however,  in  this,  that  friendship,  according  to 
the  Philosopher  [Ethic,  viii.)  is  like  a  habit,  whereas  love 
and  dilection  are  expressed  by  way  of  act  or  passion;  and 
charity  can  be  taken  either  way. 

Moreover  these  three  express  act  in  different  ways. 
For  love  has  a  wider  signification  than  the  others,  since 
every  dilection  or  charity  is  love,  but  not  vice  versa.  Because 
dilection  implies,  in  addition  to  love,  a  choice  (electionem) 
made  beforeliand,  as  the  very  word  denotes:  and  therefore 


3i6  QUESTION  XXVI 

diiection  is  not  in  the  concupiscible  power,  but  only  in  the 
will,  and  only  in  the  rational  nature. — Charity  denotes,  in 
addition  to  love  a  certain  perfection  of  love,  in  so  far  as 
that  which  is  loved  is  held  to  be  of  great  price,  as  the  word 
itself  implies.* 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Dionysius  is  speaking  of  love  and  diiection, 
in  so  far  as  they  are  in  the  intellectual  appetite;  for  thus 
love  is  the  same  as  diiection. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  object  of  love  is  more  general  than  the 
object  of  diiection:  because  love  extends  to  more  than 
diiection  does,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Love  and  diiection  differ,  not  in  respect  of 
good  and  evil,  but  as  stated.  Yet  in  the  intellectual  faculty 
love  is  the  same  as  diiection.  And  it  is  in  this  sense  that 
Augustine  speaks  of  love  in  the  passage  quoted:  hence  a  little 
further  on  he  adds  that  a  right  will  is  well  directed  love,  and  a 
wrong  will  is  ill-directed  love.  However,  the  fact  that  love 
which  is  a  concupiscible  passion,  inclines  many  to  evil,  is  the 
reason  why  some  assigned  the  difference  stated  above  (06/.  3). 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  The  reason  why  some  held  that,  even  when 
applied  to  the  will  itself,  the  word  love  signifies  something 
more  Godlike  than  diiection,  was  because  love  denotes  a 
passion,  especially  in  so  far  as  it  is  in  the  sensitive  appetite; 
whereas  diiection  presupposes  the  judgment  of  reason. 
But  it  is  possible  for  man  to  tend  to  God  by  love,  being  as  it 
were  passively  drawn  by  Him,  more  than  he  can  possibly 
be  drawn  thereto  by  his  reason,  which  pertains  to  the  nature 
of  diiection,  as  stated  above.  And  consequently  love  is 
more  Godlike  than  diiection. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  love  is  properly  divided  into  love  of 
friendship  and  love  of  concupiscence  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  love  is  not  properly  divided 
into   love  of  friendship   and   love   of  concupiscence.     For 

*  Referring  to  the  Latin  carus  (dear). 


LOVE,  IN  ITSELF  317 

love  is  a  passion,  while  friendship  is  a  habit,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  {Ethic,  viii.).  But  habit  cannot  be  the  member 
of  a  division  of  passions.  Therefore  love  is  not  properly 
divided  into  love  of  concupiscence  and  love  of  friendship. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  a  thing  cannot  be  divided  by  another 
member  of  the  same  division;  for  man  is  not  a  member  of 
the  same  division  as  animal.  But  concupiscence  is  a  member 
of  the  same  division  as  love,  as  a  passion  distinct  from  love. 
Therefore  concupiscence  is  not  a  division  of  love. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  according  to  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  viii.) 
friendship  is  threefold,  that  which  is  founded  on  usefulness, 
that  which  is  founded  on  pleasure,  and  that  which  is  founded 
on  goodness.  But  useful  and  pleasant  friendship  are  not 
without  concupiscence.  Therefore  concupiscence  should 
not  be  contrasted  with  friendship. 

On  the  contrary,  We  are  said  to  love  certain  things,  because 
we  desire  them:  thus  a  man  is  said  to  love  wine,  on  account 
of  its  sweetness  which  he  desires  ;  as  stated  in  Topic,  ii. 
But  we  have  no  friendship  for  wine  and  suchlike  things,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  viii.  Therefore  love  of  concupiscence  is 
distinct  from  love  of  friendship. 

/  ansii)er  that,  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.),  to  love  is 
to  wish  good  to  someone.  Hence  the  movement  of  love  has 
a  twofold  tendency :  towards  the  good  which  a  man  wishes 
to  someone, — to  himself  or  to  another;  and  towards  that  to 
which  he  wishes  some  good.  Accordingly,  man  has  love  of 
concupiscence  towards  the  good  that  he  wishes  to  another ; 
and  love  of  friendship,  towards  him  to  whom  he  wishes  good. 

Now  the  members  of  this  division  are  related  as  primary 
and  secondary:  since  that  which  is  loved  with  the  love  of 
friendship  is  love  simply  and  for  itself ;  whereas  that  which  is 
loved  with  the  love  of  concupiscence,  is  loved,  not  simply  and 
for  itself,  but  for  something  else.  For  just  as  that  which  has 
existence,  is  a  being  simply,  while  that  which  exists  in  another 
is  a  relative  being ;  so,  because  good  is  convertible  with  being, 
the  good,  which  itself  has  goodness,  is  good  simply;  but  that 
which  is  another's  good,  is  a  relative  good.  Consequently 
the  love  with  which  a  thing  is  loved,  that  it  may  have  some 


3i8  QUESTION  XXVI 

good,  is  love  simply:  while  the  love,  with  which  a  thing  is 
loved,  that  it  may  be  another's  good,  is  relative  love. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Love  is  not  divided  into  friendship  and 
concupiscence,  but  into  love  of  friendship,  and  love  of  con- 
cupiscence. For  a  friend  is,  properly  speaking,  one  to  whom 
we  wish  good :  while  we  are  said  to  desire,  what  we  wish  for 
ourselves. 

Hence  the  Reply  to  the  Second  Objection  is  evident. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  When  friendship  is  based  on  usefulness 
or  pleasure,  a  man  does  indeed  wish  his  friend  some  good: 
and  in  this  respect  the  character  of  friendship  is  preserved. 
But  since  he  refers  this  good  further  to  his  own  pleasure  or 
use,  the  result  is  that  friendship  of  the  useful  or  pleasant,  in 
so  far  as  it  is  connected  with  love  of  concupiscence,  loses 
the  character  of  true  friendship. 


QUESTION  XXVII. 

OF  TPIE  CAUSE  OF  LOVE. 

{In  Four  Article s.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  cause  of  love:  and  under  this 
head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  good 
is  the  only  cause  of  love  ?  (2)  Whether  knowledge  is  a 
cause  of  love  ?  (3)  Whether  likeness  is  a  cause  of  love  ? 
(4)  Whether  any  other  passion  of  the  soul  is  the  cause  of 
love  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  good  is  the  only  cause  of  love  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  good  is  not  the  only  cause  of 
love.  For  good  does  not  cause  love,  except  because  it  is 
loved.  But  it  happens  that  evil  also  is  loved,  according  to 
Ps.  X.  6:  He  that  loveth  iniquity y  hateth  his  own  soul :  else, 
every  love  would  be  good.  Therefore  good  is  not  the  only 
cause  of  love. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.)  that 
we  love  those  who  acknowledge  their  evils.  Therefore  it  seems 
that  evil  is  the  cause  of  love. 

Ohj,  3.  Further,  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Nom.  iv.)  that  not 
the  good  only  but  also  the  beautiful  is  beloved  by  all. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Trin.  viii.) :  Assuredly, 
the  good  alone  is  beloved.  Therefore  good  alone  is  the  cause 
of  love. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXVI.,  A.  i),  Love 
belongs  to  the  appetitive  power  which  is  a  passive  faculty. 
Wherefore  its  object  stands  in  relation  to  it  as  the  cause  of 
its  movement  or  act.     Therefore  the  cause  of  love  must 

319 


320  QUESTION  XXVII 

needs  be  love's  object.  Now  the  proper  object  of  love  is 
the  good;  because,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXVI.,  AA.  i,  2), 
love  implies  a  certain  connaturalness  or  complacency  of  the 
lover  for  the  thing  beloved ;  and  to  everything,  that  thing  is  a 
good,  which  is  akin  and  proportionate  to  it.  It  follows, 
therefore,  that  good  is  the  proper  cause  of  love. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Evil  is  never  loved  except  under  the  aspect 
of  good,  that  is  to  say,  in  so  far  as  it  is  good  in  some  respect, 
and  is  considered  as  being  good  simply.  And  thus  a  certain 
love  is  evil,  in  so  far  as  it  tends  to  that  which  is  not  simply 
a  true  good.  It  is  in  this  way  that  man  loves  iniquity,  in- 
asmuch as,  by  means  of  iniquity,  some  good  is  gained; 
pleasure,  for  instance,  or  money,  or  suchlike. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Those  who  acknowledge  their  evils,  are 
beloved,  not  for  their  evils,  but  because  they  acknowledge 
them,  for  it  is  a  good  thing  to  acknowledge  one's  faults,  in 
so  far  as  it  excludes  insincerity  or  hyprocrisy. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  beautiful  is  the  same  as  the  good, 
and  they  differ  in  aspect  only.  For  since  good  is  what  all 
seek,  the  notion  of  good  is  that  which  calms  the  desire;  while 
the  notion  of  the  beautiful  is  that  which  calms  the  desire,  by 
being  seen  or  known .  Consequently  those  senses  chiefly  regard 
the  beautiful,  which  are  the  most  cognitive,  viz.,  sight  and 
hearing,  as  ministering  to  reason ;  for  we  speak  of  beautiful 
sights  and  beautiful  sounds.  But  in  reference  to  the  other 
objects  of  the  other  senses,  we  do  not  use  the  expression 
heautiful,  for  we  do  not  speak  of  beautiful  tastes,  and  beauti- 
ful odours.  Thus  it  is  evident  that  beauty  adds  to  goodness 
a  relation  to  the  cognitive  faculty :  so  that  good  means  that 
which  simply  pleases  the  appetite;  while  the  beautiful  is 
something  pleasant  to  apprehend. 

Second  Article, 
whether  knowledge  is  a  cause  of  love  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — • 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  knowledge  is  not  a  cause  of  love. 
For  it  is  due  to  love  that  a  thing  is  sought.     But  some  things 


THE  CAUSE  OF  LOVE  321 

are  sought  without  being  known,  for  instance,  the  sciences ; 
for  since  to  have  them  is  the  same  as  to  know  them,  as  Augustine 
says  (Qq.  83),  if  we  knew  them  we  should  have  them,  and 
should  not  seek  them.  Therefore  knowledge  is  not  the  cause 
of  love. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  to  love  what  we  know  not  seems  like 
loving  something  more  than  we  know  it.  But  some  things 
are  loved  more  than  they  are  known:  thus  in  this  life  God 
can  be  loved  in  Himself,  but  cannot  be  known  in  Himself. 
Therefore  knowledge  is  not  the  cause  of  love. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  knowledge  were  the  cause  of  love,  there 
would  be  no  love,  where  there  is  no  knowledge.  But  in  all 
things  there  is  love,  as  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Nom.  iv.); 
whereas  there  is  not  knowledge  in  all  things.  Therefore 
knowledge  is  not  the  cause  of  love. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  proves  (De  Tvin.  x.)  that  none 
can  love  what  he  does  not  know. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  good  is  the  cause  of 
love,  as  being  its  object.  But  good  is  not  the  object  of  the 
appetite,  except  as  apprehended.  And  therefore  love  de- 
mands some  apprehension  of  the  good  that  is  loved.  For 
this  reason  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  ix.)  says  that  bodily  sight 
is  the  beginning  of  sensitive  love:  and  in  like  manner  the 
contemplation  of  spiritual  beauty  or  goodness  is  the  be- 
ginning of  spiritual  love.  Accordingly  knowledge  is  the 
cause  of  love  for  the  same  reason  as  good  is,  which  can  be 
loved  only  if  known. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  He  who  seeks  science,  is  not  entirely  without 
knowledge  thereof:  but  knows  something  about  it  already 
in  some  respect,  either  in  a  general  way,  or  in  some  one  of  its 
effects,  or  from  having  heard  it  commended,  as  Augustine 
says  (De  Trin.  x.).  But  to  have  it  is  not  to  know  it  thus, 
but  to  know  it  perfectly. 

Reply  Oh].  2.  Something  is  required  for  the  perfection  of 
knowledge,  that  is  not  requisite  for  the  perfection  of  love. 
For  knowledge  belongs  to  the  reason,  whose  function  con- 
sists in  distinguishing  things  which  in  reality  are  united,  and 
in  uniting  together,  after  a  fashion,  things  that  are  distinct, 

II.  I  21 


32  2  QUESTION  XXVII 

by  comparing  one  with  another.  Consequently  the  per- 
fection of  knowledge  requires  that  man  should  know  dis- 
tinctly all  that  is  in  a  thing,  such  as  its  parts,  powers,  and 
properties.  On  the  other  hand,  love  is  in  the  appetitive 
power,  which  regards  a  thing  as  it  is  in  itself:  wherefore  it 
suffices,  for  the  perfection  of  love,  that  a  thing  be  loved 
according  as  it  is  known  in  itself.  Hence  it  is,  therefore, 
that  a  thing  is  loved  more  than  it  is  known ;  since  it  can  be 
loved  perfectly,  even  without  being  perfectly  known.  This 
is  most  evident  in  regard  to  the  sciences,  which  some  love 
through  having  a  certain  general  knowledge  of  them:  for 
instance,  they  know  that  rhetoric  is  a  science  that  enables 
man  to  persuade  others;  and  this  is  what  they  love  in 
rhetoric.     The  same  apphes  to  the  love  of  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Even  natural  love,  which  is  in  all  things,  is 
caused  by  a  kind  of  knowledge,  not  indeed  existing  in 
natural  things  themselves,  but  in  Him  Who  created  their 
nature,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXVL,  A.  i;  cf.  P.  i,  Q.  VI., 
A.  I  ad  2). 

Third  Article, 
w^hether  likeness  is  a  cause  of  love  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  likeness  is  not  a  cause  of  love. 
For  the  same  thing  is  not  the  cause  of  contraries.  But 
likeness  is  the  cause  of  hatred;  for  it  is  written  (Prov.  xiii.  10) 
that  among  the  proud  there  are  always  contentions  ;  and  the 
Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  viii.)  that  potters  quarrel  with  one 
another.     Therefore  likeness  is  not  a  cause  of  love. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Augustine  says  {Confess,  iv.)  that  a  man 
loves  in  another  that  which  he  would  not  he  himself :  thus  he 
loves  an  actor,  hut  would  not  himself  he  an  actor.  But  it 
would  not  be  so,  if  likeness  were  the  proper  cause  of  love;  for 
in  that  case  a  man  would  love  in  another,  that  which  he 
possesses  himself,  or  would  like  to  possess.  Therefore  like- 
ness is  not  a  cause  of  love. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Everyone  loves  that  which  he  needs, 
even  if  he  have  it  not :  thus  a  sick  man  loves  health,  and  a 


THE  CAUSE  OF  LOVE  323 

poor  man  loves  riches.  But  in  so  far  as  he  needs  them  and 
lacks  them,  he  is  unlike  them.  Therefore  not  only  likeness 
but  also  unlikeness  is  a  cause  of  love. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.)  that  we 
love  those  who  bestow  money  and  health  on  us;  and  also  those 
who  retain  their  friendship  for  the  dead.  But  all  are  not  such. 
Therefore  likeness  is  not  a  cause  of  love. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ecclus.  xiii.  19) :  Every  beast 
loveth  its  like. 

I  answer  that,  Likeness,  properly  speaking,  is  a  cause  of 
love.  But  it  must  be  observed  that  likeness  between  things 
is  twofold.  One  kind  of  likeness  arises  from  each  thing 
having  the  same  quality  actually:  for  example,  two  things 
possessing  the  quality  of  whiteness  are  said  to  be  alike. 
Another  kind  of  likeness  arises  from  one  thing  having 
potentially  and  by  way  of  inclination,  a  quality  which  the 
other  has  actually:  thus  we  may  say  that  a  heavy  body 
existing  outside  its  proper  place  is  like  another  heavy  body 
that  exists  in  its  proper  place :  or  again,  according  as  poten- 
tiality bears  a  resemblance  to  its  act ;  since  act  is  contained, 
in  a  manner,  in  the  potentiality  itself. 

Accordingly  the  first  kind  of  likeness  causes  love  of  friend- 
ship or  well-wishing.  For  the  very  fact  that  two  men  are 
alike,  having,  as  it  were,  one  form,  makes  them  to  be,  in  a 
manner,  one  in  that  form :  thus  two  men  are  one  thing  in  the 
species  of  humanity,  and  two  white  men  are  one  thing  in 
whiteness.  Hence  the  affections  of  one  tend  to  the  other, 
as  being  one  with  him;  and  he  wishes  good  to  him  as  to 
himself.  But  the  second  kind  of  likeness  causes  love  of 
concupiscence,  or  friendship  founded  on  usefulness  or  plea- 
sure: because  whatever  is  in  potentiality,  as  such,  has  the 
desire  for  its  act;  and  it  takes  pleasure  in  its  realization,  if 
it  be  a  sentient  and  cognitive  being. 

Now  it  has  been  stated  above  (Q.  XX VL,  A.  4),  that  in 
the  love  of  concupiscence,  the  lover,  properly  speaking, 
loves  himself,  in  willing  the  good  that  he  desires.  But  a 
man  loves  himself  more  than  another :  because  he  is  one  with 
himself  substantially,  whereas  with  another  he  is  one  only 


324  QUESTION  XXVII 

in  the  likeness  of  some  form.  Consequently,  if  this  other's 
likeness  to  him  arising  from  the  participation  of  a  form, 
hinders  him  from  gaining  the  good  that  he  loves,  he  becomes 
hateful  to  him,  not  for  being  like  him,  but  for  hindering  him 
from  gaining  his  own  good.  This  is  why  potters  quarrel 
among  themselves,  because  they  hinder  one  another's  gain: 
and  why  there  are  contentions  among  the  proud,  because  they 
hinder  one  another  in  attaining  the  position  they  covet. 

Hence  the  Reply  to  the  First  Objection  is  evident. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Even  when  a  man  loves  in  another  what  he 
loves  not  in  himself,  there  is  a  certain  likeness  of  proportion: 
because  as  the  latter  is  to  that  which  is  loved  in  him,  so  is 
the  former  to  that  which  he  loves  in  himself :  for  instance,  if 
a  good  singer  love  a  good  writer,  we  can  see  a  likeness  of 
proportion,  inasmuch  as  each  one  has  that  which  is  becoming 
to  him  in  respect  of  his  art. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  He  that  loves  what  he  needs,  bears  a  like- 
ness to  wliat  he  loves,  as  potentiality  bears  a  likeness  to  its 
act,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  According  to  the  same  likeness  of  poten- 
tiality to  its  act,  the  illiberal  man  loves  the  man  who  is 
liberal,  in  so  far  as  he  expects  from  him  that  which  he  desires. 

The  same  applies  to  the  man  who  is  constant  in  his  friend- 
ship as  compared  to  one  who  is  inconstant.  For  in  either 
case  friendship  seems  to  be  based  on  usefulness.  We  might 
also  say  that  although  not  all  men  have  these  virtues  in  the 
complete  habit,  yet  they  have  them  according  to  certain 
seminal  principles  in  the  reason,  in  force  of  which  principles 
the  man  who  is  not  virtuous  loves  the  virtuous  man,  as 
being  in  conformity  with  his  own  natural  reason. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  any  other  passion  of  the  soul  is  a 
cause  of  love  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 
Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  some  other  passion  of  the  soul 
ran.  be  the  cause  of  love.     For  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  viii.) 


THE  CAUSE  OF  LOVE  325 

says  that  some  are  loved  for  the  sake  of  the  pleasure  they 
give.  But  pleasure  is  a  passion.  Therefore  another  passion 
is  a  cause  of  love. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  desire  is  a  passion.  But  we  love  some 
because  we  desire  to  receive  something  from  them:  as 
happens  in  every  friendship  based  on  usefulness.  There- 
fore another  passion  is  a  cause  of  love. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  {De  Trin.  x.):  When  we 
have  no  hope  of  getting  a  thing,  we  love  it  hut  half-heartedly  or 
not  at  all,  even  if  we  see  how  beautiful  it  is. 

On  the  contrary.  All  the  other  emotions  of  the  soul  are 
caused  by  love,  as  Augustine  says  {De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.). 

/  answer  that,  There  is  no  other  passion  of  the  soul  that 
does  not  presuppose  love  of  some  kind.  The  reason  is  that 
every  other  passion  of  the  soul  denotes  either  movement 
towards  something,  or  rest  in  something.  Now  every 
movement  towards  something,  or  rest  in  something,  arises 
from  some  kinship  or  aptness  to  that  thing;  and  in  this  does 
love  consist.  Therefore  it  is  not  possible  for  any  other 
passion  of  the  soul  to  be  universally  the  cause  of  every  love. 
But  it  may  happen  that  some  other  passion  is  the  cause  of 
some  particular  love :  just  as  one  good  is  the  cause  of  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  When  a  man  loves  a  thing  for  the  pleasure 
it  affords,  his  love  is  indeed  caused  by  pleasure;  but  that 
very  pleasure  is  caused,  in  its  turn,  by  another  preceding 
love;  for  none  takes  pleasure  save  in  that  which  is  loved  in 
some  way. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Desire  for  a  thing  always  presupposes  love 
for  that  thing.  But  desire  of  one  thing  can  be  the  cause  of 
another  thing  being  loved:  thus  he  that  desires  money,  for 
this  reason  loves  him  from  whom  he  receives  it. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Hope  causes  or  increases  love;  both  by 
reason  of  pleasure,  because  it  causes  pleasure ;  and  by  reason 
of  desire,  because  hope  strengthens  desire,  since  we  do  not 
desire  so  intensely  that  which  we  have  no  hope  of  receiving. 
Nevertheless  hope  itself  is  of  a  good  that  is  loved. 


QUESTION  XXVIII. 

OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  LOVE. 

{In  Six  Articles.) 

We  now  have  to  consider  the  effects  of  love:  under  which 
head  there  are  six  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  union  is  an 
effect  of  love  ?  (2)  Whether  mutual  indwelling  is  an  effect 
of  love  ?  (3)  Whether  extasy  is  an  effect  of  love  ?  (4) 
Whether  zeal  is  an  effect  of  love  ?  (5)  Whether  love  is  a 
passion  that  is  hurtful  to  the  lover  ?  (6)  Whether  love  is 
cause  of  all  that  the  lover  does  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  union  is  an  effect  of  love  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  union  is  not  an  effect  of  love. 
For  absence  is  incompatible  with  union.  But  love  is  com- 
patible with  absence;  for  the  Apostle  says  (Gal.  iv.  18):  Be 
zealous  for  that  which  is  good  in  a  good  thing  always  (speaking 
of  himself,  according  to  a  gloss),  and  not  only  when  I  am 
present  with  you.     Therefore  union  is  not  an  effect  of  love. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  every  union  is  either  according  to  essence, 
— thus  form  is  united  to  matter,  accident  to  subject,  and  a 
part  to  the  whole,  or  to  another  part  in  order  to  make  up  the 
whole :  or  according  to  likeness,  in  genus,  species,  or  accident. 
But  love  does  not  cause  union  of  essence ;  else  love  could  not 
be  between  things  essentially  distinct.  On  the  other  hand, 
love  does  not  cause  union  of  likeness,  but  rather  is  caused  by 
it,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXVII.,  A.  3).  Therefore  union  is 
not  an  effect  of  love. 

326 


THE  EFFECTS  OF  LOVE  327 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  sense  in  act  is  the  sensible  in  act,  and 
the  intellect  in  act  is  the  thing  actually  understood.  But 
the  lover  in  act  is  not  the  beloved  in  act.  Therefore  union 
is  the  effect  of  knowledge  rather  than  of  love. 

On  the  contrary,  Dionysius  says  [Div.  Nom.  iv.)  that  every 
love  is  a  unitive  force. 

I  ansiiDer  that,  The  union  of  lover  and  beloved  is  twofold. 
The  first  is  real  union ;  for  instance,  when  the  beloved  is  in 
the  presence  of  the  lover. — The  second  is  union  of  affection : 
and  this  union  must  be  considered  in  relation  to  the  pre- 
ceding apprehension;  since  movement  of  the  appetite 
follows  apprehension.  Now  love  being  twofold,  viz.,  love 
of  concupiscence,  and  love  of  friendship;  each  of  these  arises 
from  a  kind  of  apprehension  of  union  between  lover  and 
beloved.  For  when  we  love  a  thing,  by  desiring  it,  we  appre- 
hend it  as  belonging  to  our  well-being.  In  like  manner  when 
a  man  loves  another  with  the  love  of  friendship,  he  wills 
good  to  him,  just  as  he  wills  good  to  himself:  wherefore  he 
apprehends  him  as  his  other  self,  in  so  far,  to  wit,  as  he  wills 
good  to  him  as  to  himself.  Hence  a  friend  is  called  a  man's 
other  self  {Ethic,  ix.),  and  Augustine  says  (Confess,  iv.).  Well 
did  one  say  to  his  friend  :  Thou  half  of  my  soul. 

The  first  of  these  unions  is  caused  effectively  by  love; 
because  love  moves  man  to  desire  and  seek  the  presence  of 
the  beloved,  as  of  something  suitable  and  belonging  to  him. 
The  second  union  is  cdiused  formally  by  love;  because  love 
itself  is  this  union  or  bond.  In  this  sense  Augustine  says 
(De  Trin.  viii.)  that  love  is  a  vital  principle  uniting,  or  seeking 
to  unite  two  together,  the  lover,  to  wit,  and  the  beloved.  For  in 
describing  it  as  uniting  he  refers  to  the  union  of  affection, 
without  which  there  is  no  love:  and  in  saying  that  it  seeks 
to  unite,  he  refers  to  real  union. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  argument  is  true  of  real  union,  which 
is  requisite  as  causing  pleasure;  while  desire  implies  the  real 
absence  of  the  beloved:  whereas  love  remains  whether  the 
beloved  be  absent  or  present. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Union  has  a  threefold  relation  to  love. 
There  is  a  union  winch  causes  love;  and  this  is  substantial 


328  QUESTION  XXVIII 

union,  as  regards  the  love  with  which  one  loves  oneself; 
while  as  regards  the  love  wherewith  one  loves  other  things,  it 
is  the  union  of  likeness,  as  stated  above  (0.  XXVII.,  A.  3). 
There  is  also  a  union  which  is  essentially  love  itself.  This 
union  is  according  to  a  bond  of  affection,  and  is  likened  to 
substantial  union,  inasmuch  as  the  lover  stands  to  the  object 
of  his  love,  as  to  himself,  if  it  be  love  of  friendship;  as  to 
something  belonging  to  himself,  if  it  be  love  of  concupiscence. 
Again  there  is  a  union,  which  is  the  effect  of  love.  This  is 
real  union,  which  the  lover  seeks  with  the  object  of  his  love. 
Moreover  this  union  is  in  keeping  with  the  demands  of  love : 
for  as  the  Philosopher  relates  (Polit.  ii.),  Aristophanes  stQ.ted 
that  lovers  would  wish  to  be  united  both  into  one,  but  since  this 
would  result  in  either  one  or  both  being  destroyed,  they  seek  a 
suitable  and  becoming  union; — ^to  live  together,  speak  to- 
gether, and  be  united  in  other  like  things. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Knowledge  is  perfected  by  the  thing  known 
being  united,  through  its  likeness,  to  the  knower.  But  the 
effect  of  love  is  that  the  thing  itself  which  is  loved,  is,  in  a 
way,  united  to  the  lover,  as  stated  above.  Consequently 
the  union  caused  by  love  is  closer  than  that  which  is  caused 
by  knowledge. 

Second  Article, 
whether  mutual  indwelling  is  an  effect  of  love  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  love  does  not  cause  mutual  in- 
dwelling, so  that  the  lover  be  in  the  beloved  and  vice  versa. 
For  that  which  is  in  another  is  contained  by  it.  But  the 
same  cannot  be  container  and  contents.  Therefore  love 
cannot  cause  mutual  indwelling,  so  that  the  lover  be  in  the 
beloved  and  vice  versa. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  nothing  can  penetrate  within  a  whole, 
except  by  means  of  a  division  of  the  whole.  But  it  is  the 
function  of  the  reason,  not  of  the  appetite  where  love 
resides,  to  divide  things  that  are  really  united.  Therefore 
mutual  indwelling  is  not  an  effect  of  love. 


THE  EFFECTS  OF  LOVE  329 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  love  involves  the  lover  being  in  the 
beloved  and  vice  versa,  it  follows  that  the  beloved  is  united 
to  the  lover,  in  the  same  way  as  the  lover  is  united  to  the 
beloved.  But  the  union  itself  is  love,  as  stated  above  (A.  i). 
Therefore  it  follows  that  the  lover  is  always  loved  by  the 
object  of  his  love;  which  is  evidently  false.  Therefore 
mutual  indwelling  is  not  an  effect  of  love. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (i  John  iv.  16):  He  that 
ahideth  in  charity  ahideth  in  God,  and  God  in  him.  Now 
charity  is  the  love  of  God.  Therefore,  for  the  same  reason, 
every  love  makes  the  beloved  to  be  in  the  lover,  and  vice 
versa. 

/  answer  that,  This  effect  of  mutual  indwelling  may  be 
understood  as  referring  either  to  the  apprehensive  or  to  the 
appetitive  power.  Because,  as  to  the  apprehensive  power, 
the  beloved  is  said  to  be  in  the  lover,  inasmuch  as  the 
beloved  abides  in  the  apprehension  of  the  lover,  according 
to  Phil.  i.  7,  For  that  I  have  you  in  my  heart  :  while  the  lover 
is  said  to  be  in  the  beloved,  according  to  apprehension,  inas- 
much as  the  lover  is  not  satisfied  with  a  superficiaF  appre- 
hension of  the  beloved,  but  strives  to  gain  an  intimate 
knowledge  of  everything  pertaining  to  the  beloved,  so  as  to 
penetrate  into  his  very  soul.  Thus  it  is  written  concerning 
the  Holy  Ghost,  Who  is  God's  Love,  that  He  searcheth  all 
things,  yea  the  deep  things  of  God  (i  Cor.  ii.  10). 

As  to  the  appetitive  power,  the  object  loved  is  said  to  be 
in  the  lover,  inasmuch  as  it  is  in  his  affections,  by  a  kind  of 
complacency :  causing  him  either  to  take  pleasure  in  it,  or  in 
its  good,  when  present ;  or,  in  the  absence  of  the  object  loved, 
by  his  longing,  to  tend  towards  it  with  the  love  of  concu- 
piscence, or  towards  the  good  that  he  wills  to  the  beloved,  with 
the  love  of  friendship :  not  indeed  from  any  extrinsic  cause 
(as  when  we  desire  one  thing  on  account  of  another,  or  wish 
good  to  another  on  account  of  something  else),  but  because 
the  complacency  in  the  beloved  is  rooted  in  the  lover's  heart. 
For  this  reason  we  speak  of  love  as  being  intimate ;  and  of  the 
how  els  of  charity.  On  the  other  hand,  the  lover  is  in  the 
beloved,  by  the  love  of  concupiscence  and  by  the  love  of 


330  QUESTION  XXVIII 

friendship,  but  not  in  the  same  way.  For  the  love  of  con- 
cupiscence is  not  satisfied  with  any  external  or  superficial 
possession  or  enjoyment  of  the  beloved;  but  seeks  to  possess 
the  beloved  perfectly,  by  penetrating  into  his  heart,  as  it 
were.  Whereas,  in  the  love  of  friendship,  the  lover  is  in  the 
beloved,  inasmuch  as  he  reckons  w^hat  is  good  or  evil  to  his 
friend,  as  being  so  to  himself ;  and  his  friend's  will  as  his  own, 
so  that  it  seems  as  though  he  felt  the  good  or  suffered  the 
evil  in  the  person  of  his  friend.  Hence  it  is  proper  to 
friends  to  desire  the  same  things,  and  to  grieve  and  rejoice  at  the 
same,  as  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  ix.  and  Rhet.  ii.). 
Consequently  in  so  far  as  he  reckons  what  affects  his  friend 
as  affecting  himself,  the  lover  seems  to  be  in  the  beloved,  as 
though  he  were  become  one  with  him :  but  in  so  far  as,  on 
the  other  hand,  he  wills  and  acts  for  his  friend's  sake  as  for 
his  own  sake,  looking  on  his  friend  as  identified  with  himself, 
thus  the  beloved  is  in  the  lover. 

In  yet  a  third  way,  mutual  indwelling  in  the  love  of  friend- 
ship can  be  understood  in  regard  to  reciprocal  love:  inas- 
much as  friends  return  love  for  love,  and  both  desire  and  do 
good  things  for  one  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  beloved  is  contained  in  the  lover,  by 
being  impressed  on  his  heart  and  thus  becoming  the  object 
of  his  complacency.  On  the  other  hand,  the  lover  is  con- 
tained in  the  beloved,  inasmuch  as  the  lover  penetrates,  so 
to  speak,  into  the  beloved.  For  nothing  hinders  a  thing 
from  being  both  container  and  contents  in  different  ways: 
just  as  a  genus  is  contained  in  its  species,  and  vice  versa. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  apprehension  of  the  reason  precedes  the 
movement  of  love.  Consequently,  just  as  the  reason  divides, 
so  does  the  movement  of  love  penetrate  into  the  beloved,  a;? 
was  explained  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  argument  is  true  of  the  third  kind  of 
mutual  indwelling,  which  is  not  to  be  found  in  every  kind  of 
love. 


THE  EFFECTS  OF  LOVE  331 

Third  Article, 
whether  extasy  is  an  effect  of  love  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  extasy  is  not  an  effect  of  love. 
For  extasy  seems  to  imply  loss  of  reason.  But  love  does 
not  always  result  in  loss  of  reason :  for  lovers  are  masters  of 
themselves  at  times.     Therefore  love  does  not  cause  extasy. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  lover  desires  to  be  united  to  the 
beloved.  Therefore  he  draws  the  beloved  to  himself,  rather 
than  betakes  himself  into  the  beloved,  going  forth  out  from 
himself  as  it  were. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  love  unites  the  beloved  to  the  lover,  as 
stated  above  (A.  i).  If,  therefore,  the  lover  goes  out  from 
himself,  in  order  to  betake  himself  into  the  beloved,  it 
follows  that  the  lover  always  loves  the  beloved  more  than 
himself:  which  is  evidently  false.  Therefore  extasy  is  not 
an  effect  of  love. 

On  the  contrary,  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Nom.  iv.)  that  the 
Divine  love  produces  extasy,  and  that  God  Himself  suffered 
extasy  through  love.  Since  therefore  according  to  the  same 
author  {ibid.),  every  love  is  a  participated  likeness  of  the 
Divine  Love,  it  seems  that  every  love  causes  extasy. 

/  answer  that,  To  suffer  extasy  means  to  be  placed  outside 
oneself.  This  happens  as  to  the  apprehensive  power  and 
as  to  the  appetitive  power.  As  to  the  apprehensive 
power,  a  man  is  said  to  be  placed  outside  himself,  when 
he  is  placed  outside  the  knowledge  proper  to  him.  This 
may  be  due  to  his  being  raised  to  a  higher  knowledge; 
thus,  a  man  is  said  to  suffer  extasy,  inasmuch  as  he  is 
placed  outside  the  connatural  apprehension  of  his  sense  and 
reason,  when  he  is  raised  up  so  as  to  comprehend  things 
that  surpass  sense  and  reason :  or  it  may  be  due  to  his  being 
cast  down  into  a  state  of  debasement;  thus  a  man  may  be 
said  to  suffer  extasy,  when  he  is  overcome  by  violent  passion 
or  madness,- — As  to  the  appetitive  power,  a  man  is  said  to 
suffer  extasy,  when  that  power  is  borne  towards  something 
else,  so  that  it  goes  forth  out  from  itself,  as  it  were. 


332  QUESTION  XXVIII 

The  first  of  these  extasies  is  caused  by  love  dispositively, 
in  so  far  namely,  as  love  makes  the  beloved  to  dwell  in  the 
lover's  mind,  as  stated  above  (A.  2) :  while  the  more  we 
give  our  mind  to  one  thing,  the  less  we  think  of  others. — The 
second  extasy  is  caused  by  love  directly;  by  love  of  friend- 
ship, simply;  by  love  of  concupiscence,  not  simply  but  in  a 
restricted  sense.  Because  in  love  of  concupiscence,  the 
lover  is  taken  out  from  himself,  in  a  certain  sense ;  in  so  far, 
namely,  as  not  being  satisfied  with  enjoying  the  good  that  he 
has,  he  seeks  to  enjoy  something  outside  himself.  But  since 
he  seeks  to  have  this  extrinsic  good  for  himself,  he  does  not 
go  out  from  himself  simply,  and  this  movement  remains 
finally  within  him.  On  the  other  hand,  in  the  love  of  friend- 
ship, a  man's  affection  goes  out  from  itself  simply;  because 
he  wishes  and  does  good  to  his  friend,  as  it  were,  caring  and 
providing  for  him,  for  his  sake. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  argument  is  true  of  the  first  kind  of 
extasy. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  This  argument  applies  to  love  of  concu- 
piscence, which,  as  stated  above,  does  not  cause  extasy 
simply. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  He  who  loves,  goes  out  from  himself,  in  so 
far  as  he  wills  the  good  of  his  friend  and  works  for  it.  Yet 
he  does  not  will  the  good  of  his  friend  more  than  his  own 
good :  and  so  it  does  not  follow  that  he  loves  another  more 
than  himself. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  zeal  is  an  effect  of  love  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i .  It  seems  that  zeal  is  not  an  effect  of  love.  For 
zeal  is  a  beginning  of  contention;  wherefore  it  is  written 
(i  Cor.  iii.  3):  Whereas  there  is  among  you  zeal  (Douay, — 
envying)  and  contention,  etc.  But  contention  is  incom- 
patible with  love.     Therefore  zeal  is  not  an  effect  of  love. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  object  of  love  is  the  good,  which 
communicates  itself  to  others.  But  zeal  is  opposed  to 
communication;  since  it  seems  an  effect  of  zeal,  that  a  man 


THE  EFFECTS  OF  LOVE  333 

refuses  to  share  the  object  of  his  love  with  another:  thus 
husbands  are  said  to  be  jealous  of  (zelare)  their  wives, 
because  they  will  not  share  them  with  others.  Therefore 
zeal  is  not  an  effect  of  love. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  there  is  no  zeal  without  hatred,  as  neither 
is  there  without  love:  for  it  is  written  (Fs.  Ixxii.  3) :  /  had  a 
zeal  on  occasion  of  the  wicked.  Therefore  it  should  not  be  set 
down  as  an  effect  of  love  any  more  than  of  hatred. 

On  the  contrary,  Dionysius  says  {Div.  Nom.  iv.):  God  is 
said  to  he  a  zealot,  on  account  of  this  great  love  for  all  things. 

I  ansi^jer  that,  Zeol,  whatever  way  we  take  it,  arises  from 
the  intensity  of  love.  For  it  is  evident  that  the  more  in- 
tensely a  power  tends  to  anything,  the  more  vigorously  it 
withstands  opposition  or  resistance.  Since  therefore  love 
is  a  movement  toi<uards  the  object  loved,  as  Augustine  says 
(Qq.  83),  an  intense  love  seeks  to  remove  everything  that 
opposes  it. 

But  this  happens  in  different  ways  according  to  love  of 
concupiscence,  and  love  of  friendship.  For  in  love  of  con- 
cupiscence he  who  desires  something  intensely,  is  moved 
against  all  that  hinders  his  gaining  or  quietly  enjoying  the 
object  of  his  love.  It  is  thus  that  husbands  are  said  to  be 
jealous  of  their  wives,  lest  association  with  others  prove  a 
hindrance  to  their  exclusive  individual  rights.  In  like 
manner  those  who  seek  to  excel,  are  moved  against  those  who 
seem  to  excel,  as  though  these  were  a  hindrance  to  their 
excelling.  And  this  is  the  zeal  of  envy,  of  which  it  is  written 
(Ps.  xxxvi.  i) :  Be  not  emulous  of  evil  doers,  nor  envy  (zelaveris) 
them  that  work  iniquity. 

On  the  other  hand,  love  of  friendship  seeks  the  friend's 
good:  wherefore,  when  it  is  intense,  it  causes  a  man  to  be 
moved  against  everything  that  opposes  the  friend's  good.  In 
this  respect,  a  man  is  said  to  be  zealous  on  behalf  of  his 
friend,  when  he  makes  a  point  of  repelling  whatever  may 
be  said  or  done  against  his  friend's  good.  In  this  way,  too, 
a  man  is  said  to  be  zealous  on  God's  behalf,  when  he  en- 
deavours, to  the  best  of  his  means,  to  repel  whatever  is 
contrary  to  the  honour  or  will  of  God;  according  to  3  Kings 


334  QUESTION  XXVIII 

xix.  14 :  With  zeal  have  I  been  zealous  for  the  Lord  .  .  .  of  hosts. 
Again  on  the  words  of  John  ii.  17 :  The  zeal  of  Thy  house  hath 
eaten  me  up,  di.  gloss  says  that  a  man  is  eaten  up  imth  a  good 
zeal,  who  strives  to  remedy  whatever  evil  he  perceives  ;  and  if 
he  cannot,  hears  with  it  and  laments  it. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  Apostle  is  speaking  in  this  passage  of  the 
zeal  of  envy;  which  is  indeed  the  cause  of  contention,  not 
against  the  object  of  love,  but  for  it,  and  against  that  which 
is  opposed  to  it. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Good  is  loved  inasmuch  as  it  can  be  com- 
municated to  the  lover.  Consequently  whatever  hinders 
the  perfection  of  this  communication,  becomes  hateful. 
Thus  zeal  arises  from  love  of  good. — But  through  defect  of 
goodness,  it  happens  that  certain  small  goods  cannot,  in  their 
entirety,  be  possessed  by  many  at  the  same  time :  and  from 
the  love  of  such  things  arises  the  zeal  of  envy.  But  it  does 
not  arise,  properly  speaking,  in  the  case  of  those  things 
which,  in  their  entirety,  can  be  possessed  by  many:  for  no 
one  envies  another  the  knowledge  of  truth,  which  can  be 
known  entirely  by  many;  except  perhaps  one  may  envy 
another  the  excellence  of  his  knowledge  of  some  truth. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  very  fact  that  a  man  hates  whatever  is 
opposed  to  the  object  of  his  love,  is  the  effect  of  love.  Hence 
zeal  is  set  down  as  an  effect  of  love  rather  than  of  hatred. 

Fifth  Article.  * 
whether  love  is  a  passion  that  wounds  the 

.    LOVER  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  love  wounds  the  lover.  For 
languor  denotes  a  hurt  in  the  one  that  languishes.  But 
love  causes  languor:  for  it  is  written  (Cant.  ii.  5):  Compass 
me  about  with  apples  ;  because  I  languish  with  love.  There- 
fore love  is  a  wounding  passion. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  melting  is  a  kind  of  dissolution.  But  love 
melts  that  in  which  it  is:  for  it  is  written  (Cant.  v.  6):  My 
soul  melted  when  my  beloved  spoke.     Therefore  love  is  a 


THE  EFFECTS  OF  LOVE  335 

dissolvent:  therefore  it  is  a  corruptive  and  a  wounding 
passion. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  fervour  denotes  a  certain  excess  of  heat; 
which  excess  has  a  corruptive  effect.  But  love  causes 
fervour:  for  Dionysius  {Co^L  Hier.  vii.)  in  reckoning  the 
properties  belonging  to  the  Seraphim's  love,  includes  heat, 
piercing  and  most  fervent.  Moreover  it  is  said  of  love 
(Cant.  viii.  6)  that  its  lamps  are  fire  and  flames.  Therefore 
love  is  a  wounding  and  corruptive  passion. 

On  the  contrary,  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Nom.  iv.)  that  every- 
thing loves  itself  with  a  love  that  holds  it  together,  i.e.,  that 
preserves  it.  Therefore  love  is  not  a  wounding  passion,  but 
rather  one  that  preserves  and  perfects. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXVI.,  AA.  i.  2, 
Q.  XXVIL,  A.  i),  love  denotes  a  certain  adapting  of  the 
appetitive  power  to  some  good.  Now  nothing  is  hurt  by 
being  adapted  to  that  which  is  suitable  to  it;  rather,  if 
possible,  it  is  perfected  and  bettered.  But  if  a  thing  be 
adapted  to  that  which  is  not  suitable  to  it,  it  is  hurt  and 
made  worse  thereby.  Consequently  love  of  a  suitable  good 
perfects  and  betters  the  lover;  but  love  of  a  good  which  is 
unsuitable  to  the  lover,  wounds  and  worsens  him.  Where- 
fore man  is  perfected  and  bettered  chiefly  by  the  love  of 
God:  but  is  wounded  and  worsened  by  the  love  of  sin,  ac- 
cording to  Osee  ix.  10:  They  became  abominable,  as  those 
things  which  they  loved. 

And  let  this  be  understood  as  applying  to  love  in  respect 
of  its  formal  element,  i.e.,  in  regard  to  the  appetite.  But  in 
respect  of  the  material  element  in  the  passion  of  love,  i.e.,  a 
certain  bodily  change,  it  happens  that  love  is  hurtful,  by 
reason  of  this  change  being  excessive:  just  as  it  happens  in 
the  senses,  and  in  every  act  of  a  power  of  the  soul  that  is 
exercised  through  the  change  of  some  bodily  organ. 

In  reply  to  the  objections,  it  is  to  be  observed  that  four 
proximate  effects  may  be  ascribed  to  love:  viz.,  melting, 
enjoyment,  languor,  and  fervour.  Of  these  the  first  is 
melting,  which  is  opposed  to  freezing.  For  things  that  are 
frozen,  are  closely  bound  together,  so  as  to  be  hard  to  pierce. 


336  QUESTION  XXVIII 

But  it  belongs  to  love  that  the  appetite  is  fitted  to  receive 
the  good  which  is  loved,  inasmuch  as  the  object  loved  is  in 
the  lover,  as  stated  above  (A.  2).  Consequently  the  freezing 
or  hardening  of  the  heart  is  a  disposition  incompatible  with 
love :  while  melting  denotes  a  softening  of  the  heart,  whereby 
the  heart  shows  itself  to  be  ready  for  the  entrance  of  the 
beloved. — If,  then,  the  beloved  is  present  and  possessed, 
pleasure  or  enjoyment  ensues.  But  if  the  beloved  be  absent, 
two  passions  arise;  viz.,  sadness  at  its  absence,  which  is 
denoted  by  languor  (hence  Tully  in  De  Tuscul.  Qucest.  iii. 
applies  the  term  ailment  chiefly  to  sadness) ;  and  an  intense 
desire  to  possess  the  beloved,  which  is  signified  by  fervour. 
— And  these  are  the  effects  of  love  considered  formally, 
according  to  the  relation  of  the  appetitive  power  to  its  object. 
But  in  the  passion  of  love,  other  effects  ensue,  proportionate 
to  the  above,  in  respect  of  a  change  in  the  organ. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  love  is  cause  of  all  that  the 
lover  does  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  lover  does  not  everything 
from  love.  For  love  is  a  passion,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXI. 
A.  2).  But  man  does  not  do  everything  from  passion:  but 
some  things  he  does  from  choice;  and  some  things  from 
ignorance,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  v.  Therefore  man  does  not 
everything  that  he  does,  from  love. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  appetite  is  a  principle  of  movement 
and  action  in  all  animals,  as  stated  in  De  Anima  iii.  If, 
therefore,  whatever  a  man  does,  is  done  from  love,  the  other 
passions  of  the  appetitive  faculty  are  superfluous. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  nothing  is  produced  at  one  and  the  same 
time  by  contrary  causes.  But  some  things  are  done  from 
hatred.     Therefore  all  things  are  not  done  from  love. 

On  the  contrary,  Dionysius  says  [Div.  Nom.  iv.)  that  all 
things,  whatever  they  do,  they  do  for  the  love  of  good. 

I  answer  that.  Every  agent  acts  for  an  end,  as  stated  above 


THE  EFFECTS  OF  LOVE  337 

(Q.  I.,  A.  2).  Now  the  end  is  the  good  desired  and  loved  by 
each  one.  Wherefore  it  is  evident  that  every  agent,  what- 
ever it  be,  does  every  action  from  love  of  some  kind. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  objection  takes  love  as  a  passion  exist- 
ing in  the  sensitive  appetite.  But  here  we  are  speaking  of 
love  in  a  general  sense,  inasmuch  as  it  includes  intellectual, 
rational,  animal,  and  natural  love:  for  it  is  in  this  sense  that 
Dionysius  speaks  of  love  in  chap.  iv.  of  De  Divinis  Nomini- 
bus. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  As  stated  above  (A.  5:  Q.  XXVII. ,  A.  4) 
desire,  sadness  and  pleasure,  and  consequently  all  the  other 
passions  of  the  soul,  result  from  love.  Wherefore  every  act 
that  proceeds  from  any  passion,  proceeds  also  from  love  as 
from  a  first  cause:  and  so  the  other  passions,  which  are 
proximate  causes,  are  not  superfluous. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Hatred  also  is  a  result  of  love,  as  we  shall 
state  further  on  (Q.  XXIX.,  A.  2). 


II.   I  2i 


QUESTION  XXIX. 

OF  HATRED. 

{In  Six  Ay  tides.) 

We  must  now  consider  hatred :  concerning  which  there  are 
six  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  evil  is  the  cause  and  the 
object  of  hatred  ?  (2)  Whether  love  is  the  cause  of  hatred  ? 
(3)  Whether  hatred  is  stronger  than  love  ?  (4)  Whether  a 
man  can  hate  himself  ?  (5)  Whether  a  man  can  hate  the 
truth  ?  (6)  Whether  a  thing  can  be  the  object  of  universal 
hatred  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  evil  is  the  cause  and  object  of 

HATRED  ? 

We  proceed  thiis  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  evil  is  not  the  object  and  cause 
of  hatred.  For  everything  that  exists,  as  such,  is  good.  If 
therefore  evil  be  the  object  of  hatred,  it  follows  that  nothing 
but  the  lack  of  something  can  be  the  object  of  hatred: 
which  is  clearly  untrue. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  hatred  of  evil  is  praiseworthy;  hence 
(2  Machab.  iii.  i)  some  are  praised  for  that  the  laws  were  very 
well  kept,  because  of  the  godliness  of  Onias  the  high-priest,  and 
the  hatred  their  souls  (Douay,  his  soul)  had  of  evil.  If,  there- 
fore, nothing  but  evil  be  the  object  of  hatred,  it  would  follow 
that  all  hatred  is  commendable:  and  this  is  clearly  false. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  same  thing  is  not  at  the  same  time 
both  good  and  evil.  But  the  same  thing  is  lovable  and 
hateful  to  different  subjects.  Therefore  hatred  is  not  only 
of  evil,  but  also  of  good. 

338 


OF  HATRED  339 

On  the  contrary.  Hatred  is  the  opposite  of  love.  But  the 
object  of  love  is  good,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXVI.,  A.  i; 
Q.  XX Vn.,  A.  i).     Therefore  the  object  of  hatred  is  evil. 

/  answer  that,  Since  the  natural  appetite  is  the  result  of 
apprehension  (though  this  apprehension  is  not  in  the  same 
subject  as  the  natural  appetite),  it  seems  that  what  applies 
to  the  inclination  of  the  natural  appetite,  applies  also  to  the 
animal  appetite,  which  does  result  from  an  apprehension  in 
the  same  subject,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXVI.,  A.  i).  Now, 
with  regard  to  the  natural  appetite,  it  is  evident,  that  just  as 
each  thing  is  naturally  attuned  and  adapted  to  that  which  is 
suitable  to  it,  wherein  consists  natural  love;  so  has  it  a 
natural  dissonance  from  that  which  opposes  and  destroys  it ; 
and  this  is  natural  hatred.  So,  therefore,  in  the  animal 
appetite,  or  in  the  intellectual  appetite,  love  is  a  certain 
harmony  of  the  appetite  with  that  which  is  apprehended  as 
suitable;  while  hatred  is  dissonance  of  the  appetite  from  that 
which  is  apprehended  as  repugnant  and  hurtful.  Now, 
just  as  whatever  is  suitable,  as  such,  bears  the  aspect  of 
good;  so  whatever  is  repugnant,  as  such,  bears  the  aspect  of 
evil.  And  therefore,  just  as  good  is  the  object  of  love,  so 
evil  is  the  object  of  hatred. 

Re-ply  Ohj.  i.  Being,  as  such,  has  not  the  aspect  of  re- 
pugnance but  only  of  fittingness ;  because  being  is  common 
to  all  things.  But  being,  inasmuch  as  it  is  this  determinate 
being,  has  an  aspect  of  repugnance  to  some  determinate 
being.  And  in  this  way,  one  being  is  hateful  to  another, 
and  is  evil;  though  not  in  itself,  but  by  comparison  with 
something  else. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Just  as  a  thing  may  be  apprehended  as 
good,  when  it  is  not  truly  good;  so  a  thing  may  be  appre- 
hended as  evil,  whereas  it  is  not  truly  evil.  Hence  it  happens 
sometimes  that  neither  hatred  of  evil  nor  love  of  good  is 
good. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  To  different  things  the  same  thing  may  be 
lovable  or  hateful:  in  respect  of  the  natural  appetite, 
owing  to  one  and  the  same  thing  being  naturally  suitable  to 
one  thing,  and  naturally  unsuitable  to  another:  thus  heat  is 


340  QUESTION  XXIX 

becoming  to  fire  and  unbecoming  to  water:  and  in  respect 
of  the  animal  appetite,  owing  to  one  and  the  same  thing 
being  apprehended  by  one  as  good,  by  another  as  bad. 

Second  Article, 
whether  love  is  a  cause  of  hatred  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  love  is  not  a  cause  of  hatred. 
For  the  opposite  members  of  a  division  are  naturally  simul- 
taneous {Prcedic.  x.).  But  love  and  hatred  are  opposite 
members  of  a  division,  since  they  are  contrary  to  one 
another.  Therefore  they  are  naturally  simultaneous.  There- 
fore love  is  not  the  cause  of  hatred. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  of  two  contraries,  one  is  not  the  cause  of 
the  other.  But  love  and  hatred  are  contraries.  Therefore 
love  is  not  the  cause  of  hatred. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  that  which  follows  is  not  the  cause  of  that 
which  precedes.  But  hatred  precedes  love,  seemingly: 
since  hatred  denotes  a  turning  away  from  evil,  whereas  love 
denotes  a  turning  towards  good.  Therefore  love  is  not  the 
cause  of  evil. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  that  all 
emotions  are  caused  by  love.  Therefore  hatred  also,  since 
it  is  an  emotion  of  the  soul,  is  caused  by  love. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  love  consists  in  a 
certain  agreement  of  the  lover  with  the  object  loved,  while 
hatred  consists  in  a  certain  disagreement  or  dissonance. 
Now  we  should  consider  in  each  thing,  what  agrees  with  it, 
before  that  which  disagrees:  since  a  thing  disagrees  with 
another,  through  destroying  or  hindering  that  which  agrees 
with  it.  Consequently  love  must  needs  precede  hatred;  and 
nothing  is  hated,  save  through  being  contrary  to  a  suitable 
thing  which  is  loved.  And  hence  it  is  that  every  hatred  is 
caused  by  love. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  opposite  members  of  a  division  are 
sometimes  simultaneous  naturally,  both  really  and  logically ; 
e.g.,  two  species  of  animal,  or  two  species  of  colour.     Some- 


OF  HATRED  341 

times  they  are  simultaneous  logically,  while,  in  reality,  one 
precedes,  and  causes  the  other;  e.g.,  the  species  of  numbers, 
figures  and  movements.  Sometimes  they  are  not  simul- 
taneous either  really  or  logically;  e.g.,  substance  and  acci- 
dent ;  for  substance  is  in  reality  the  cause  of  accident ;  and 
being  is  predicated  of  substance  before  it  is  predicated  of 
accident,  by  a  priority  of  reason,  because  it  is  not  predicated 
of  accident  except  inasmuch  as  the  latter  is  in  substance. — 
Now  love  and  hatred  are  naturally  simultaneous,  logically 
but  not  really.  Wherefore  nothing  hinders  love  from  being 
the  cause  of  hatred. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Love  and  hatred  are  contraries  if  considered 
in  respect  of  the  same  thing.  But  if  taken  in  respect  of 
contraries,  they  are  not  themselves  contrary,  but  conse- 
quent to  one  another:  for  it  amounts  to  the  same  that  one 
love  a  certain  thing,  or  that  one  hate  its  contrary.  Thus 
love  of  one  thing  is  the  cause  of  one's  hating  its  contrary. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  In  the  order  of  execution,  the  fact  of  turning 
away  from  one  term  precedes  the  fact  of  turning  towards  the 
other.  But  the  reverse  is  the  case  in  the  order  of  intention : 
since  approach  to  one  term  is  the  reason  for  turning  away 
from  the  other.  Now  the  appetitive  movement  belongs 
rather  to  the  order  of  intention  than  to  that  of  execution. 
Wherefore  love  precedes  hatred:  because  each  is  an  appeti- 
tive movement. 

Third  Article, 
whether  hatred  is  stronger  than  love  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  hatred  is  stronger  than  love. 
For  Augustine  says  (Qq.  83) :  There  is  no  one  who  does  not  flee 
from  pain,  more  than  he  desires  pleasure.  But  flight  from 
sorrow  pertains  to  hatred;  while  desire  for  pleasure  belongs 
to  love.     Therefore  hatred  is  stronger  than  love. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  weaker  is  overcome  by  the  stronger. 
But  love  is  overcome  by  hatred :  when,  that  is  to  say,  love  is 
turned  into  hatred.     Therefore  hatred  is  stronger  than  love. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  emotions  of  the  soul  are  gauged  by 


343  QUESTION  XXIX 

their  effects.  But  man  insists  more  on  repelling  what  is 
hateful,  than  on  seeking  what  is  pleasant :  thus  also  irrational 
animals  refrain  from  pleasure  for  fear  of  the  whip,  as  Augus- 
tine instances  {loc.  cit.).  Therefore  hatred  is  stronger  than 
love. 

On  the  contrary,  Good  is  stronger  than  evil;  because  evil 
does  nothing  except  in  virtue  of  good,  as  Dionysius  says  (Div. 
Nom.  iv.).  But  hatred  and  love  differ  according  to  the 
difference  of  good  and  evil.  Therefore  hatred  is  stronger 
than  love. 

/  answer  that,  It  is  impossible  for  an  effect  to  be  stronger 
than  its  cause.  Now  every  hatred  arises  from  some  love 
as  its  cause,  as  above  stated  (A.  2).  Therefore  it  is  impos- 
sible for  hatred  to  be  stronger  than  love  simply. 

But  furthermore,  love  must  needs  be  simply  stronger  than 
hatred.  Because  a  thing  is  moved  to  the  end  more  strongly 
than  to  the  means.  Now  turning  away  from  evil  is  directed 
as  a  means  to  the  gaining  of  good.  Wherefore,  simply 
speaking,  the  soul's  movement  in  respect  of  good  is  stronger 
than  its  movement  in  respect  of  evil. 

Nevertheless  hatred  sometimes  seems  to  be  stronger  than 
love,  for  two  reasons.  First,  because  hatred  is  more  keenly 
felt  than  love.  For,  since  the  sensitive  perception  is  accom- 
panied by  a  certain  impression;  when  once  the  impression 
has  been  received  it  is  not  felt  so  keenly  as  in  the  moment  of 
receiving  it.  Hence  the  heat  of  a  hectic  fever,  though 
greater,  is  nevertheless  not  felt  so  much  as  the  heat  of  a 
tertian  fever ;  because  the  heat  of  the  hectic  fever  is  habitual 
and  like  a  second  nature.  For  this  reason,  love  is  felt  more 
keenly  in  the  absence  of  the  object  loved;  thus  Augustine 
says  {De  Trin.  x.)  that  love  is  felt  more  keenly,  when  we  lack 
what  we  love.  And  for  the  same  reason,  the  unbecom- 
ingness  of  that  which  is  hated  is  felt  more  keenly,  than  the 
becomingness  of  that  which  is  loved. — Secondly,  because 
comparison  is  made  between  a  hatred  and  a  love  which  are 
not  mutually  corresponding.  Because,  according  to  different 
degrees  of  good  there  are  different  degrees  of  love  to  which 
correspond  different  degrees  of  hatred.     Wherefore  a  hatred 


OF  HATRED  343 

that  corresponds  to  a  greater  love,  moves  us  more  than  a 
lesser  love. 

Hence  it  is  clear  how  to  reply  to  the  First  Objection.  For 
the  love  of  pleasure  is  less  than  the  love  of  self-preservation, 
to  which  corresponds  flight  from  sorrow.  Wherefore  we 
flee  from  pain  more  than  we  love  pleasure. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Hatred  would  never  overcome  love,  were  it 
not  for  the  greater  love  to  which  that  hatred  corresponds. 
Thus  man  loves  himself,  more  than  he  loves  his  friend :  and 
because  he  loves  himself,  his  friend  is  hateful  to  him,  if  he 
oppose  him. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  reason  why  we  act  with  greater  insis- 
tence in  repelling  what  is  hateful,  is  because  we  feel  hatred 
more  keenly. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  a  man  can  hate  himself  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  man  can  hate  himself.  For 
it  is  written  (Ps.  x.  6):  He  that  loveth  iniquity,  hateth  his  own 
soul.  But  many  love  iniquity.  Therefore  many  hate  them- 
selves. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  him  we  hate,  to  whom  we  wish  and  work 
evil.  But  sometimes  a  man  wishes  and  works  evil  to  him- 
self; e.g.,  a  man  who  kills  himself.  Therefore  some  men 
hate  themselves. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Boethius  says  (De  Consol.  ii.)  that  avarice 
makes  a  man  hateful ;  whence  we  may  conclude  that  every- 
one hates  a  miser.  But  some  men  are  misers.  Therefore 
they  hate  themselves. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Eph.  v.  29)  that  no  man 
ever  hated  his  own  flesh. 

I  answer  that,  Properly  speakings  it  is  impossible  for  a  man 
to  hate  himself.  For  everything  naturally  desires  good,  nor 
can  anyone  desire  anything  for  himself,  save  under  the  aspect 
of  good :  for  evil  is  outside  the  scope  of  the  will,  as  Dionysius 
says  {Div.  Norn.  iv.).  Now  to  love  a  man  is  to  will  good  to 
him,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXVL,  A.  4).     Consequently,  a 


344  QUESTION  XXIX 

man  must,  of  necessity,  love  himself;  and  it  is  impossible 
for  a  man  to  hate  himself,  properly  speaking. 

But  accidentally  it  happens  that  a  man  hates  himself: 
and  this  in  two  ways.  First,  on  the  part  of  the  good  which 
a  man  wills  to  himself.  For  it  happens  sometimes  that  what 
is  desired  as  good  in  some  particular  respect,  is  simply  evil ; 
and  in  this  way,  a  man  accidentally  wills  evil  to  himself; 
and  thus  hates  himself. — Secondly,  in  regard  to  himself,  to 
whom  he  wills  good.  For  each  thing  is  that  which  is  pre- 
dominant in  it;  wherefore  the  state  is  said  to  do  what  the 
king  does,  as  if  the  king  were  the  whole  state.  Now  it  is 
clear  that  man  is  principally  the  mind  of  man.  And  it 
happens  that  some  men  account  themselves  as  being 
principally  that  which  they  are  in  their  material  and  sensi- 
tive nature.  Wherefore  they  love  themselves  according  to 
what  they  take  themselves  to  be,  while  they  hate  that 
which  they  really  are,  by  desiring  what  is  contrary  to 
reason. — And  in  both  these  ways,  he  that  loveth  iniquity 
hateth  not  onlv  his  own  soul,  but  also  himself. 

Wherefore  the  reply  to  the  First  Objection  is  evident. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  No  man  wills  and  works  evil  to  himself, 
except  he  apprehend  it  under  the  aspect  of  good.  For  even 
they  who  kill  themselves,  apprehend  death  itself  as  a  good, 
considered  as  putting  an  end  to  some  unhappiness  or  pain. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  miser  hates  something  accidental  to 
himself,  but  not  for  that  reason  does  he  hate  himself:  thus 
a  sick  man  hates  his  sickness  for  the  very  reason  that  he 
loves  himself. — Or  we  may  say  that  avarice  makes  man 
hateful  to  others,  but  not  to  himself.  In  fact,  it  is  caused 
by  inordinate  self-love,  ir  respect  of  which,  man  desires 
temporal  goods  for  himself  more  than  he  should. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  a  man  can  hate  the  truth  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  man  cannot  hate  the  truth. 
For  good,  true,   and  being  are  convertible.      But  a  man 


OF  HATRED  345 

cannot  hate  good.  Neither,  therefore,  can  he  hate  the 
truth. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  All  men  have  a  natural  desire  for  know- 
ledge, as  stated  in  the  beginning  of  Metaph.  i.  But  know- 
ledge is  only  of  truth.  Therefore  truth  is  naturally  desired 
and  loved.  But  that  which  is  in  a  thing  naturally,  is  always 
in  it.     Therefore  no  man  can  hate  the  truth. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhetor,  ii.)  that 
men  love  those  who  are  straightforward.  But  there  can  be  no 
other  motive  for  this  save  truth.  Therefore  man  loves  the 
truth  naturally.     Therefore  he  cannot  hate  it. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Gal.  iv.  16):  Am  I 
become  your  enemy  because  I  tell  you  the  truth  ?* 

/  answer  that,  Good,  true  and  being  are  the  same  in  reality, 
but  differ  as  considered  by  reason.  For  good  is  considered 
in  the  light  of  something  desirable,  while  being  and  true  are 
not  so  considered:  because  good  is  what  all  things  seek. 
Wherefore  good,  as  such,  cannot  be  the  object  of  hatred, 
neither  in  general  nor  in  particular. — Being  and  truth  in 
general  cannot  be  the  object  of  hatred :  because  disagreement 
is  the  cause  of  hatred,  and  agreement  is  the  cause  of  love; 
while  being  and  truth  are  common  to  all  things.  But 
nothing  hinders  some  particular  being  or  some  particular 
truth  being  an  object  of  hatred,  in  so  far  as  it  is  considered  as 
hurtful  and  repugnant;  since  hurtfulness  and  repugnance 
are  not  incompatible  with  the  notion  of  being  and  truth, 
as  they  are  with  the  notion  of  good. 

Now  it  may  happen  in  three  ways  that  some  particular 
truth  is  repugnant  or  hurtful  to  the  good  we  love.  First, 
according  as  truth  is  in  things  as  in  its  cause  and  origin. 
And  thus  man  sometimes  hates  a  particular  truth,  when  he 
wishes  that  what  is  true  were  not  true. — Secondly,  according 
as  truth  is  in  man's  knowledge,  which  hinders  him  from 
gaining  the  object  loved:  such  is  the  case  of  those  who  wish 
not  to  know  the  truth  of  faith,  that  they  may  sin  freely; 
in  whose  person  it  is  said  (Job  xxi.  14):  Depart  from  us,  we 

*  St.  Thomas  quotes  the  passage,  probably  from  memory,  as 
though  it  were  an  assertion:  /  am  become,  etc. 


346  QUESTION  XXIX 

desire  not  the  knowledge  of  Thy  ways.- — Thirdly,  a  particular 
truth  is  hated  inasmuch  as  it  is  in  the  intellect  of  another 
man :  as,  for  instance,  when  a  man  wishes  to  remain  hidden 
in  his  sin,  he  hates  that  anyone  should  know  the  truth  about 
his  sin.  In  this  respect,  Augustine  says  {Confess,  x.)  that 
men  love  truth  when  it  enlightens,  they  hate  it  when  it  reproves. 
This  suffices  for  the  Reply  to  the  First  Objection. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  knowledge  of  truth  is  lovable  in  itself: 
hence  Augustine  says  that  men  love  it  when  it  enlightens. 
But  accidentally,  the  knowledge  of  truth  may  become  hateful, 
in  so  far  as  it  hinders  one  from  accomplishing  one's  desire. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  reason  why  we  love  those  who  are 
straightforward  is  because  they  tell  the  truth,  the  knowledge 
of  which  is  lovable  for  its  own  sake. 

Sixth  Article, 
whether  anything  can  be  an  object  of  universal 

HATRED  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  thing  cannot  be  an  object  of 
universal  hatred.  Because  hatred  is  a  passion  of  the  sensi- 
tive appetite,  which  is  moved  by  an  apprehension  in  the 
senses.  But  the  senses  cannot  apprehend  the  universal. 
Tlierefore  a  thing  cannot  be  an  object  of  universal  hatred. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  hatred  is  caused  by  disagreement;  and 
where  there  is  disagreement,  there  is  nothing  in  common. 
But  the  notion  of  universality  implies  something  in  common. 
Therefore  nothing  can  be  the  object  of  universal  hatred. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  object  of  hatred  is  evil.  But  evil  is 
in  things,  and  not  in  the  mind  (Metaph.  vi.).  Since  therefore 
the  universal  is  in  the  mind  only,  which  abstracts  the  uni- 
versal from  the  particular,  it  seems  that  hatred  cannot  have 
a  universal  object. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Philosopher  says  (Rhetor,  ii.)  that  anger 
is  directed  to  something  singular,  whereas  hatred  is  also  directed 
to  a  thing  in  general ;  for  everybody  hates  the  thief  and  the  back- 
biter. 

I  answer  that,  There  are  two  ways  of  speaking  of  the  uni- 


OF  HATRED  347 

versal:  first,  as  considered  under  the  aspect  of  universality; 
secondly,  as  considered  in  the  nature  to  which  it  is  ascribed : 
for  it  is  one  thing  to  consider  the  universal  man,  and  another 
to  consider  a  man  as  man.  If,  therefore,  we  take  the  uni- 
versal, in  the  first  way,  no  sensitive  power,  whether  of  appre- 
hension or  of  appetite,  can  attain  the  universal :  because  the 
universal  is  obtained  by  abstraction  from  individual  matter, 
on  which  every  sensitive  power  is  based. 

Nevertheless  the  sensitive  powers,  both  of  apprehension 
and  of  appetite,  can  tend  to  something  universally.  Thus 
we  say  that  the  object  of  sight  is  colour  considered  generic- 
ally;  not  that  the  sight  is  cognizant  of  universal  colour,  but 
because  the  fact  that  colour  is  cognizable  by  the  sight,  is 
attributed  to  colour  not  as  being  this  particular  colour,  but 
simply  because  it  is  colour.  Accordingly  hatred  in  the 
sensitive  faculty  can  regard  something  universally :  because 
this  thing,  by  reason  of  its  common  nature,  and  not  merely 
as  an  individual,  is  hostile  to  the  animal — for  instance,  a 
wolf  in  regard  to  a  sheep.  Hence  a  sheep  hates  the  wolf 
universally. — ^On  the  other  hand,  anger  is  always  caused  by 
something  in  particular :  because  it  is  caused  by  some  action 
of  the  one  that  hurts  us;  and  actions  proceed  from  indi- 
viduals. For  this  reason  the  Philosopher  says  that  anger 
is  always  directed  to  something  singular,  whereas  hatred  can 
he  directed  to  a  thing  in  general. 

But  according  as  hatred  is  in  the  intellectual  part,  since 
it  arises  from  the  universal  apprehension  of  the  intellect, 
it  can  regard  the  universal  in  both  ways. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  senses  do  not  apprehend  the  universal, 
as  such :  but  they  apprehend  something  in  which  the  charac- 
ter of  universality  is  discovered  by  abstraction. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  That  which  is  common  to  all  cannot  be  a 
reason  of  hatred.  But  nothing  hinders  a  thing  from  being 
common  to  many,  and  at  variance  with  others,  so  as  to  be 
hateful  to  them. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  argument  considers  the  universal 
under  the  aspect  of  universality:  and  thus  it  does  not  come 
under  the  sensitive  apprehension  or  appetite. 


QUESTION  XXX. 

OF   CONCUPISCENCE. 

[In  Four  Articles.) 

We  have  now  to  consider  concupiscence :  under  which  head 
there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  concupiscence 
is  in  the  sensitive  appetite  only  ?  (2)  Whether  concupis- 
cence is  a  specific  passion  ?  (3)  Whether  some  concupis- 
cences are  natural,  and  some  not  natural  ?  (4)  Whether 
concupiscence  is  infinite  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  concupiscence  is  in  the  sensitive  appetite 

ONLY  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  concupiscence  is  not  only  in 
the  sensitive  appetite.  For  there  is  a  concupiscence  of 
wisdom,  according  to  Wis.  vi.  21 :  The  concupiscence  (Douay, 
desire)  of  wisdom  bringeth  to  the  everlasting  kingdom.  But 
the  sensitive  appetite  can  have  no  tendency  to  wisdom. 
Therefore  concupiscence  is  not  only  in  the  sensitive  appetite. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  desire  for  the  commandments  of  God 
is  not  in  the  sensitive  appetite:  in  fact  the  Apostle  says 
(Rom.  vii.  18) :  There  dwelleth  not  in  me,  that  is  to  say,  in  my 
-flesh,  that  which  is  good.  But  desire  for  God's  command- 
ments is  an  act  of  concupiscence,  according  to  Ps.  cxviii.  20 : 
My  soul  hath  coveted  (concupivit)  to  long  for  thy  justifica- 
tion. Therefore  concupiscence  is  not  only  in  the  sensitive 
appetite. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  to  each  power,  its  proper  good  is  a  matter 

348 


OF  CONCUPISCENCE  349 

of  concupiscence.  Therefore  concupiscence  is  in  each  power 
of  the  soul,  and  not  only  in  the  sensitive  appetite. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  [De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that 
the  irrational  fart  which  is  subject  and  amenable  to  reason,  is 
divided  into  the  faculties  of  concupiscence  and  anger.  This 
is  the  irrational  part  of  the  soul,  passive  and  appetitive.  There- 
fore concupiscence  is  in  the  sensitive  appetite. 

/  answer  that.  As  the  Philosopher  says  (Rhetor,  i.),  con- 
cupiscence is  a  craving  for  that  which  is  pleasant.  Now 
pleasure  is  twofold,  as  we  shall  state  later  on  (Q.  XXXL, 
AA.  3,  4) :  one  is  in  the  intelligible  good,  which  is  the  good  of 
reason;  the  other  is  in  good  perceptible  to  the  senses.  The 
former  pleasure  seems  to  belong  to  the  soul  alone:  whereas 
the  latter  belongs  to  both  soul  and  body :  because  the  sense 
is  a  power  seated  in  a  bodily  organ :  wherefore  sensible  good 
is  the  good  of  the  whole  composite.  Now  concupiscence 
seems  to  be  the  craving  for  this  latter  pleasure,  since  it 
belongs  to  the  united  soul  and  body,  as  is  implied  by  the 
Latin  word  concupiscentia.  Therefore,  properly  speaking, 
concupiscence  is  in  the  sensitive  appetite,  and  in  the  con- 
cupiscible  faculty,  which  takes  its  name  from  it. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  craving  for  wisdom,  or  other  spiritual 
goods,  is  sometimes  called  concupiscence;  either  by  reason 
of  a  certain  likeness;  or  on  account  of  the  craving  in  the 
higher  part  of  the  soul  being  so  vehement  that  it  overflows 
into  the  lower  appetite,  so  that  the  latter  also,  in  its  own 
way,  tends  to  the  spiritual  good,  following  the  lead  of  the 
higher  appetite,  the  result  being  that  the  body  itself  tenders 
its  service  in  spiritual  matters,  according  to  Ps.  Ixxxiii.  3: 
My  heart  and  my  flesh  have  rejoiced  in  the  living  God. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Properly  speaking,  desire  may  be  not  only 
in  the  lower,  but  also  in  the  higher  appetite.  For  it  does 
not  imply  fellowship  in  craving,  as  concupiscence  does;  but 
simply  movement  towards  the  thing  desired. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  It  becomes  each  power  of  the  soul  to  seek 
its  proper  good  by  the  natural  appetite,  which  does  not  arise 
from  apprehension.  But  the  craving  for  good,  by  the 
animal  appetite,  which  arises  from  apprehension,  belongs  to 


350  QUESTION  XXX 

the  appetitive  power  alone.  And  to  crave  for  a  thing  under 
the  aspect  of  something  deUghtful  to  the  senses,  wherein 
concupiscence  properly  consists,  belongs  to  the  concupiscible 
power. 

Second  Article, 
whether  concupiscence  is  a  specific  passion  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  concupiscence  is  not  a  specific 
passion  of  the  concupiscible  power.  For  passions  are  dis- 
tinguished by  their  objects.  But  the  object  of  the  concupis- 
cible power  is  something  delightful  to  the  senses;  and  this 
is  also  the  object  of  concupiscence,  as  the  Philosopher 
declares  {Rhetor,  i.).  Therefore  concupiscence  is  not  a 
specific  power  of  the  concupiscible  faculty. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Augustine  says  (Qq.  83)  that  covetous- 
ness  is  the  love  of  transitory  things  :  so  that  it  is  not  distinct 
from  love.  But  all  specific  passions  are  distinct  from  one 
another.  Therefore  concupiscence  is  not  a  specific  passion 
in  the  concupiscible  faculty. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  to  each  passion  of  the  concupiscible 
faculty  there  is  a  specific  contrary  passion,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXIII. ,  A.  4).  But  no  specific  passion  of  the  concupis- 
cible faculty  is  contrary  to  concupiscence.  For  Damascene 
says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that  good  when  desired  gives  rise  to 
concupiscence  ;  when  present,  it  gives  joy  :  in  like  manner, 
the  evil  we  apprehend  makes  us  fear,  the  evil  that  is  present 
makes  us  sad  :  from  which  we  gather  that  as  sadness  is  con- 
trary to  joy,  so  is  fear  contrary  to  concupiscence.  But  fear 
is  not  in  the  concupiscible,  but  in  the  irascible  part.  There- 
fore concupiscence  is  not  a  specific  passion  of  the  concupis- 
cible faculty. 

On  the  contrary,  Concupiscence  is  caused  by  love,  and 
tends  to  pleasure,  both  of  which  are  passions  of  the  con- 
cupiscible faculty.  Hence  it  is  distinguished  from  the  other 
concupiscible  passions,  as  a  specific  passion. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i;  Q.  XXIII.,  A.  i), 
the  good  which  gives  pleasure  to  the  senses  is  the  common 


OF  CONCUPISCENCE  35^ 

object  of  the  concupiscible  faculty.  Hence  the  various 
concupiscible  passions  are  distinguished  according  to  the 
differences  of  that  good.  Now  the  diversity  of  this  object 
can  arise  from  the  very  nature  of  the  object,  or  from  a  diver- 
sity in  its  active  power.  The  diversity,  derived  from  the 
nature  of  the  active  object,  causes  a  material  difference  of 
passions:  while  the  difference  in  regard  to  its  active  power, 
causes  a  formal  diversity  of  passions,  in  respect  of  which 
the  passions  differ  specifically. 

Now  the  nature  of  the  motive  power  of  the  end  or  of  the 
good,  differs  according  as  it  is  really  present,  or  absent: 
because,  according  as  it  is  present,  it  causes  the  faculty  to 
find  rest  in  it;  whereas,  according  as  it  is  absent,  it  causes 
the  faculty  to  be  moved  towards  it.  Wherefore  the  object 
of  sensible  pleasure,  causes  love,  inasmuch  as,  so  to  speak, 
it  attunes  and  conforms  the  appetite  to  itself;  it  causes 
concupiscence,  inasmuch  as,  when  absent,  it  draws  the 
faculty  to  itself;  and  it  causes  pleasure,  inasmuch  as,  when 
present,  it  makes  the  faculty  to  find  rest  in  it.  Accordingly, 
concupiscence  is  a  passion  differing  in  species  from  both  love 
and  pleasure. — But  concupiscences  of  this  or  that  pleasurable 
object  differ  in  number. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Pleasurable  good  is  the  object  of  concupis- 
cence, not  absolutely,  but  considered  as  absent:  just  as 
the  sensible,  considered  as  past,  is  the  object  of  memory. 
For  these  particular  conditions  diversify  the  species  of 
passions,  and  even  of  the  powers  of  the  sensitive  part,  which 
regards  particular  things. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  In  the  passage  quoted  we  have  causal,  not 
essential,  predication :  for  covetousness  is  not  essentially  love, 
but  an  effect  of  love. — We  may  also  say  that  Augustine  is 
taking  covetousness  in  a  wide  sense,  for  any  movement  of 
the  appetite  in  respect  of  good  to  come :  so  that  it  includes 
both  love  and  hope. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  passion  which  is  directly  contrary  to 
concupiscence  has  no  name,  and  stands  in  relation  to  evil, 
as  concupiscence  in  regard  to  good.  But  since,  like  fear,  it 
regards  the  absent  evil;  sometimes  it  goes  by  the  name  of 


352  QUESTION  XXX 

fear,  just  as  hope  is  sometimes  called  covetousness.  For 
a  small  good  or  evil  is  reckoned  as  though  it  were  nothing : 
and  consequently  every  movement  of  the  appetite  to  future 
good  or  evil  is  called  hope  or  fear,  which  regard  good  and 
evil  as  arduous. 

Third  Article. 

whether  some  concupiscences  are  natural,  and  some 
^  not  natural  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  concupiscences  are  not  divided 
into  those  which  are  natural  and  those  which  are  not.  For 
concupiscence  belongs  to  the  animal  appetite,  as  stated  above 
(A.  I  ad  3).  But  the  natural  appetite  is  contrasted  with 
the  animal  appetite.   Therefore  no  concupiscence  is  natural. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  material  difference  makes  no  difference 
of  species,  but  only  numerical  difference; — a  difference 
which  is  outside  the  purview  of  science.  But  if  some  con- 
cupiscences are  natural,  and  some  not,  they  differ  only  in 
respect  of  their  objects;  which  amounts  to  a  material  differ- 
ence, which  is  one  of  number  only.  Therefore  concupis- 
cences should  not  be  divided  into  those  that  are  natural 
and  those  that  are  not. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  reason  is  contrasted  with  nature,  as  stated 
in  Phys.  ii.  If  therefore  in  man  there  is  a  concupiscence 
which  is  not  natural,  it  must  needs  be  rational.  But  this 
is  impossible:  because,  since  concupiscence  is  a  passion,  it 
belongs  to  the  sensitive  appetite,  and  not  to  the  will,  which 
is  the  rational  appetite.  Therefore  there  are  no  concupis- 
cences which  are  not  natural. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iii.  and  Rhetor,  i.) 
distinguishes  natural  concupiscences  from  those  that  are 
not  natural. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  concupiscence  is  the 
craving  for  pleasurable  good.  Now  a  thing  is  pleasurable 
in  two  ways.  First,  because  it  is  suitable  to  the  nature  of 
the  animal;  for  example,  food,  drink,  and  the  like:  and  con- 
cupiscence of  such  pleasurable  things  is  said  to  be  natural. — 


OF  CONCUPISCENCE  353 

Secondly,  a  thing  is  pleasurable  because  it  is  apprehended 
as  suitable  to  the  animal :  as  when  one  apprehends  something 
as  good  and  suitable,  and  consequently  takes  pleasure  in  it : 
and  concupiscence  of  such  pleasurable  things  is  said  to  be 
not  natural,  and  is  more  wont  to  be  called  cupidity. 

Accordingly  concupiscences  of  the  first  kind,  or  natural 
concupiscences,  are  common  to  men  and  other  animals: 
because  to  both  is  there  something  suitable  and  pleasurable 
according  to  nature :  and  in  these  all  men  agree ;  wherefore 
the  Philosopher  [Ethic,  iii.)  calls  them  common  and  necessary. 
— But  concupiscences  of  the  second  kind  are  proper  to 
men,  to  whom  it  is  proper  to  devise  something  as  good  and 
suitable,  besides  that  which  nature  requires.  Hence  the 
Philosopher  says  {Rhetor,  i.)  that  the  former  concupiscences 
are  irrational,  but  the  latter,  rational.  And  because  dif- 
ferent men  reason  differently,  therefore  the  latter  are  also 
called  {Ethic,  iii.)  proper  and  acquired,  i.e.,  in  ciddition  to 
those  that  are  natural. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  same  thing  that  is  the  object  of  the 
natural  appetite,  may  be  the  object  of  the  animal  appetite, 
once  it  is  apprehended.  And  in  this  way  there  may  be  an 
animal  concupiscence  for  food,  drink  and  the  like,  which  are 
objects  of  the  natural  appetite. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  difference  between  those  concupiscences 
that  are  natural  and  those  that  are  not,  is  not  merely  a 
material  difference;  it  is  also,  in  a  way,  formal,  in  so  far  as 
it  arises  from  a  difference  in  the  active  object.  For  the 
object  of  the  appetite  is  the  apprehended  good.  Hence 
diversity  of  apprehension  has  a  direct  bearing  on  diversity 
of  the  active  object:  according  as  a  thing  is  apprehended  as 
suitable,  either  by  absolute  apprehension,  whence  arise 
natural  concupiscences,  which  the  Philosopher  calls  irrational 
{Rhetor,  i.);  or  by  apprehension  together  with  deliberation, 
whence  arise  those  concupiscences  that  are  not  natural,  and 
which  for  this  very  reason  the  Philosopher  calls  rational 
{ibid.). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Man  has  not  only  universal  reason,  pertain- 
ing to  the  intellectual  faculty;  but  also  particular  reason, 

II.  I  23 


354  QUESTION  XXX 

pertaining  to  the  sensitive  faculty,  as  stated  in  the  First 
Part  (Q.  LXXVIIL,  A.  4;  Q.  LXXXL,  A.  3):  so  that  even 
rational  concupiscence  may  pertain  to  the  sensitive  appe- 
tite.— Moreover  the  sensitive  appetite  can  be  moved  by 
the  universal  reason  also,  through  the  means  of  the  par- 
ticular imagination. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  concupiscence  is  infinite  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  concupiscence  is  not  infinite. 
For  the  object  of  concupiscence  is  good,  which  has  the  aspect 
of  an  end.  But  where  there  is  infinity  there  is  no  end 
{Metaph.  ii.).     Therefore  concupiscence  cannot  be  infinite. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  concupiscence  is  of  the  fitting  good, 
since  it  proceeds  from  love.  But  the  infinite  is  without  pro- 
portion, and  therefore  unfitting.  Therefore  concupiscence 
cannot  be  infinite. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  there  is  no  passing  through  infinite 
things:  and  thus  there  is  no  reaching  an  ultimate  term  in 
them.  But  the  subject  of  concupiscence  is  not  delighted 
until  he  attain  the  ultimate  term.  Therefore,  if  con- 
cupiscence were  infinite,  no  delight  would  ensue. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  [Polit.  i.)  that  since 
concupiscence  is  infinite,  men  desire  an  infinite  number  of  things. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  3),  concupiscence  is 
twofold;  one  is  natural,  the  other  is  not  natural.  Natural 
concupiscence  cannot  be  actually  infinite:  because  it  is 
of  that  which  nature  requires;  and  nature  ever  tends  to 
something  finite  and  fixed.  Hence  man  never  desires 
infinite  meat,  or  infinite  drink.  —  But  just  as  in  nature 
there  is  potential  successive  infinity,  so  can  this  kind  of 
concupiscence  be  infinite  successively;  so  that,  for  instance, 
after  getting  food,  a  man  may  desire  food  yet  again ;  and  so 
of  anything  else  that  nature  requires:  because  these  bodily 
goods,  when  obtained,  do  not  last  for  ever,  but  fail.  Hence 
Our  Lord  said  to  the  woman  of  Samaria  (John  iv.  13): 
Whosoever  drinketh  of  this  water,  shall  thirst  again. 


OF  CONCUPISCENCE  355 

But  non-natural  concupiscence  is  altogether  infinite. 
Because,  as  stated  above  (A.  3)  it  follows  from  the  reason, 
and  it  belongs  to  the  reason  to  proceed  to  infinity.  Hence 
he  that  desires  riches,  may  desire  to  be  rich  beyond  a  fixed 
limit,  and  simply  to  be  as  rich  as  possible. 

Another  reason  may  be  assigned,  according  to  the  Philo- 
sopher {Polit.  i.),  why  a  certain  concupiscence  is  finite,  and 
another  infinite.  Because  concupiscence  of  the  end  is  always 
infinite;  since  the  end  is  desired  for  its  own  sake,  e.g.,  health : 
and  thus  greater  health  is  more  desired,  and  so  on  to  infinity ; 
just  as,  if  a  white  thing  of  itself  dilates  the  sight,  that  which 
is  more  white  dilates  yet  more.  On  the  other  hand,  concu- 
piscence of  the  means  is  not  infinite,  because  the  concupis- 
cence of  the  means  is  in  suitable  proportion  to  the  end. 
Consequently  those  who  place  their  end  in  riches  have  an 
infinite  concupiscence  of  riches;  whereas  those  who  desire 
riches,  on  account  of  the  necessities  of  life,  desire  a  finite 
measure  of  riches,  sufficient  for  the  necessities  of  life,  as 
the  Philosopher  says  (ibid.).  The  same  applies  to  the  con- 
cupiscence of  any  other  things. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Every  object  of  concupiscence  is  taken  as 
something  finite:  either  because  it  is  finite  in  reality,  as 
being  once  actually  desired;  or  because  it  is  finite  as 
apprehended.  For  it  cannot  be  apprehended  as  infinite, 
since  the  infinite  is  that  from  which,  however  much  we 
may  take,  there  always  remains^  something  to  be  taken 
(Phys.  iii). 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  reason  is  possessed  of  infinite  power,  in 
a  certain  sense,  in  so  far  as  it  can  consider  a  thing  infinitely, 
as  appears  in  the  addition  of  numbers  and  lines.  Conse- 
quently, the  infinite,  taken  in  a  certain  way,  is  proportionate 
to  reason.  In  fact  the  universal  which  the  reason  appre- 
hends, is  infinite  in  a  sense,  inasmuch  as  it  contains  poten- 
tially an  infinite  number  of  singulars. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  order  that  a  man  be  delighted,  there  is 
no  need  for  him  to  realize  all  that  he  desires :  for  he  delights 
in  the  realization  of  each  object  of  his  concupiscence. 


QUESTION  XXXI . 

OF  DELIGHT*  CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF. 

[In  Eight  Ay  tides.) 

We  must  now  consider  delight  and  sadness.  Concerning 
delight  four  things  must  be  considered:  (i)  Delight,  in 
itself:  (2)  The  causes  of  delight:  (3)  Its  effects:  (4)  Its  good- 
ness and  malice. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  delight  is  a  passion  ?  (2)  Whether  delight  is 
subject  to  time  ?  (3)  Whether  it  differs  from  joy  ? 
(4)  Whether  it  is  in  the  intellectual  appetite  ?  (5)  Of  the 
comparison  between  delights  of  the  higher  appetite  and 
that  of  the  lower.  (6)  Of  the  comparison  between  sensi- 
tive delights.  (7)  Whether  any  delight  is  non-natural  ? 
(8)  Whether  one  delight  can  be  contrary  to  another  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  delight  is  a  passion  ? 

W£  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  .•— 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  delight  is  not  a  passion.  For 
Damascene  {De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  distinguishes  operation 
from  passion,  and  says  that  operation  is  a  movement  in  accord 
with  nature,  while  passion  is  a  movement  contrary  to  nature. 
But  delight  is  an  operation,  according  to  the  Philosopher 
{Ethic,  vii.,  x.).     Therefore  delight  is  not  a  passion. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  To  he  passive  is  to  he  moved,  as  stated  in 
Phys.  ii.  But  delight  does  not  consist  in  being  moved,  but 
in  having  been  moved;  for  it  arises  from  good  ah'eady 
gained.     Therefore  delight  is  not  a  passion. 

*  Or,  Pleasure. 
356 


OF  DELIGHT  CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF        357 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  delight  is  a  kind  of  a  perfection  of  the 
one  who  is  dehghted;  since  it  perfects  operation,  as  stated  in 
Ethic.  X.  But  to  be  perfected  does  not  consist  in  being  pas- 
sive or  in  being  altered,  as  stated  in  Phys.  vii.  and  De 
Anima  ii.     Therefore  delight  is  not  a  passion. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  (De  Civ.  Dei  ix.,  xiv.)  reckons 
delight,  joy  or  gladness  among  the  other  passions  of  the 
soul. 

/  answer  that,  The  movements  of  the  sensitive  appetite, 
are  properly  called  passions,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXII. , 
A.  3).  Now  every  emotion  arising  from  a  sensitive  appre- 
hension, is  a  movement  of  the  sensitive  appetite:  and  this 
must  needs  be  in  what  delight  consists,  since,  according  to 
the  Philosopher  {Rhetor,  i.),  it  is  a  certain  movement  of  the 
soul  and  a  sensible  establishing  thereof  all  at  once,  in  keeping 
with  the  nature  of  the  thing. 

In  order  to  understand  this,  we  must  observe  that  just  as 
in  natural  things  some  happen  to  attain  to  their  natural 
perfections,  so  does  this  happen  in  animals.  And  though 
movement  towards  perfection  does  not  occur  all  at  once,  yet 
the  attainment  of  natural  perfection  does  occur  all  at  once. 
Now  there  is  this  difference  between  animals  and  other 
natural  things,  that  when  these  latter  are  established  in  the 
state  becoming  their  nature,  they  do  not  perceive  it,  whereas 
animals  do.  And  from  this  perception  there  arises  a  certain 
movement  of  the  soul  in  the  sensitive  appetite ;  which  move- 
ment is  called  delight.  Accordingly  by  saying  that  delight 
is  a  movement  of  the  soul,  we  designate  its  genus.  By  saying 
that  it  is  an  establishing  in  keeping  with  the  thing^s  nature, 
i.e."^,  with  that  which  exists  in  the  thing,  we  assign  the  cause 
of  delight,  viz.,  the  presence  of  a  becoming  good.  By  saying 
that  this  establishing  is  all  at  once,  we  mean  that  this  estab- 
lishing is  to  be  understood  not  as  in  the  process  of  establish- 
ment, but  as  in  the  fact  of  complete  establishment,  in  the 
term  of  the  movement,  as  it  were:  for  delight  is  not  a  be- 
coming as  Plato  maintained,  but  a  complete  fact,  as  stated 
in  Ethic,  iii.  Lastly,  by  saying  that  this  establishing  is 
sensible,  we    exclude  the  perfections  of  insensible  things 


358  QUESTION  XXXI 

wherein  there  is  no  deHght. — It  is  therefore  evident  that, 
since  delight  is  a  movement  of  the  animal  appetite  arising 
from  an  apprehension  of  sense,  it  is  a  passion  of  the  soul. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Connatural  operation,  which  is  unhindered, 
is  a  second  perfection,  as  stated  in  De  Anima  ii. :  and  there- 
fore when  a  thing  is  established  in  its  proper  connatural 
and  unhindered  operation,  delight  follows,  which  consists 
in  a  state  of  completion,  as  observed  above.  Accordingly 
when  we  say  that  delight  is  an  operation,  we  designate,  not 
its  essence,  but  its  cause. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  twofold  movement  is  to  be  observed  in 
an  animal:  one,  according  to  the  intention  of  the  end,  and 
this  belongs  to  the  appetite;  the  other,  according  to  the 
execution,  and  this  belongs  to  the  external  operation.  And 
so,  although  in  him  who  has  already  gained  the  good  in 
which  he  delights,  the  movement  of  execution  ceases,  by 
which  he  tends  to  the  end;  yet  the  movement  of  the  appeti- 
tive faculty  does  not  cease,  since,  just  as  before  it  desired 
that  which  it  had  not,  so  afterwards  does  it  delight  in  that 
which  it  possesses.  For  though  delight  is  a  certain  repose 
of  the  appetite,  if  we  consider  the  presence  of  the  pleasurable 
good  that  satisfies  the  appetite;  nevertheless  there  remains 
the  impression  made  on  the  appetite  by  its  object,  by  reason 
of  which  delight  is  a  kind  of  movement. 

Reply  Obj.  ^.  Although  the  name  of  passion  is  more  appro- 
priate to  those  passions  which  have  a  corruptive  and  evil 
tendency,  such  as  bodily  ailments,  as  also  sadness  and  fear 
in  the  soul ;  yet  some  passions  have  a  tendency  to  something 
good,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXIII.,  AA.  i,  4):  and  in  this 
sense  delight  is  called  a  passion. 

Second  Article, 
whether  delight  is  in  time  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  delight  is  in  time.  For  delight 
is  a  kind  of  movement,  as  the  Philosopher  says  (Rhetor,  i.). 
But  all  movement  is  in  time.     Therefore  delight  is  in  time. 


OF  DELIGHT  CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF        359 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  a  thing  is  said  to  last  long  and  to  be 
morose  in  respect  of  time.  But  some  pleasures  are  called 
morose.     Therefore  pleasure  is  in  time. 

Ohj .  3.  Further,  the  passions  of  the  soul  are  of  one  same 
genus.  But  some  passions  of  the  soul  are  in  time.  There- 
fore delight  is  too. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  x.)  that  no 
one  takes  pleasure  according  to  time. 

I  answer  that,  A  thing  may  be  in  time  in  two  ways:  first, 
by  itself;  secondly,  by  reason  of  something  else,  and  acci- 
dentally as  it  were.  For  since  time  is  the  measure  of  suc- 
cessive things,  those  things  are  of  themselves  said  to  be  in 
time,  to  which  succession  or  something  pertaining  to  .suc- 
cession is  essential:  such  are  movement,  repose,  speech  and 
suchlike.  On  the  other  hand,  those  things  are  said  to  be 
in  time,  by  reason  of  something  else  and  not  of  themselves, 
to  which  succession  is  not  essential,  but  which  are  subject 
to  something  successive.  Thus  the  fact  of  being  a  man  is 
not  essentially  something  successive ;  since  it  is  not  a  move- 
ment, but  the  term  of  a  movement  or  change,  viz.,  of  his 
being  begotten:  yet,  because  human  being  is  subject  to 
changeable  causes,  in  this  respect,  to  be  a  man  is  in  time. 

Accordingly,  we  must  say  that  delight,  of  itself  indeed,  is 
not  in  time:  for  it  regards  good  already  gained,  which  is, 
as  it  were,  the  term  of  the  movement.  But  if  this  good 
gained  be  subject  to  change,  the  delight  therein  will  be  in 
time  accidentally :  whereas  if  it  be  altogether  unchangeable, 
the  delight  therein  will  not  be  in  time,  either  by  reason  of 
itself  or  accidentally. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  stated  in  De  Anima  iii.,  movement  is 
twofold.  One  is  the  act  of  something  imperfect,  i.e.,  in  poten- 
tiality, as  such  :  this  movement  is  successive  and  is  in  time. 
Another  movement  is  the  act  of  something  perfect,  i.e.,  in 
act,  e.g.,  to  understand,  to  feel,  and  to  will  and  suchlike, 
also  to  delight.  This  movement  is  not  successive,  nor  is 
it  of  itself  in  time. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Delight  is  said  to  be  long  lasting  or  morose^ 
according  as  it  is  accidentally  in  time. 


36o  QUESTION  XXXI 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Other  passions  have  not  for  their  object  a 
good  obtained,  as  deUght  has.  Wherefore  there  is  more  of 
the  movement  of  the  imperfect  in  them  than  in  dehght. 
And  consequently  it  belongs  more  to  delight  not  to  be  in 
time. 

Third  Article, 
whether  delight  differs  from  joy  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  delight  is  altogether  the  same 
as  joy.  Because  the  passions  of  the  soul  differ  according  to 
their  objects.  But  delight  and  joy  have  the  same  object, 
namely,  a  good  obtained.  Therefore  joy  is  altogether  the 
same  as  delight. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  one  movement  does  not  end  in  two  terms. 
But  one  and  the  same  movement,  that  of  desire,  ends  in 
joy  and  delight.  Therefore  delight  and  joy  are  altogether 
the  same. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  joy  differs  from  delight,  it  seems  that 
there  is  equal  reason  for  distinguishing  gladness,  exultation, 
and  cheerfulness  from  delight,  so  that  they  would  all  be 
various  passions  of  the  soul.  But  this  seems  to  be  untrue. 
Therefore  joy  does  not  differ  from  delight. 

On  the  contrary,  We  do  not  speak  of  joy  in  irrational 
animals;  whereas  we  do  speak  of  delight  in  them.  There- 
fore joy  is  not  the  same  as  delight. 

I  answer  that,  Joy,  as  Avicenna  states  (De  Anima  iv.),  is 
a  kind  of  delight.  For  we  must  observe  that,  just  as  some 
concupiscences  are  natural,  and  some  not  natural,  but  con- 
sequent to  reason,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXX.,  A.  3),  so  also 
some  delights  are  natural ;  whereas  some  are  not  natural  and 
accompany  the  use  of  reason.  Or,  as  Damascene  {De  Fide 
Orthod.  ii.)  and  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius,  De  Nat.  Horn. 
xviii.)  put  it,  some  delights  are  corporeal,  some  are  animal ; 
which  amounts  to  the  same.  For  we  take  delight  both  in 
those  things  which  we  desire  naturally,  when  we  get  them, 
and  in  those  things  which  we  desire  as  a  result  of  reason. 
But  we  do  not  speak  of  joy  except  when  delight  follows 


OF  DELIGHT  CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF       361 

reason;  and  so  we  do  not  ascribe  joy  to  irrational  animals, 
but  only  delight. 

Now  whatever  we  desire  naturally,  can  also  be  the  object 
of  reasoned  desire  and  delight,  and  consequently  whatever 
can  be  the  object  of  delight,  can  also  be  the  object  of  joy  in 
rational  beings.  And  yet  everything  is  not  always  the 
object  of  joy;  since  sometimes  one  feels  a  certain  delight  in 
the  body,  without  rejoicing  thereat  according  to  reason. 
And  accordingly  delight  extends  to  more  things  than  does 
joy. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Since  the  object  of  the  animal  appetite  is 
an  apprehended  good,  diversity  of  apprehension  pertains, 
in  a  way,  to  diversity  of  the  object.  And  so  animal  delights, 
which  are  also  called  joys,  are  distinct  from  bodily  delights, 
which  are  not  called  otherwise  than  delights:  as  we  have 
observed  above  in  regard  to  concupiscence  (Q.  XXV.,  A.  3 
ad  2). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  A  like  difference  is  to  be  observed  in  con- 
cupiscences also:  so  that  delight  corresponds  to  concupis- 
cence, while  joy  corresponds  to  desire,  which  seems  to  pertain 
more  to  animal  concupiscence.  Hence  there  is  a  difference 
of  repose  corresponding  to  the  difference  of  movement. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  These  other  names  pertaining  to  delight  are 
derived  from  the  effects  of  delight;  for  Icetitia  (gladness)  is 
derived  from  the  dilatation  of  the  heart,  as  if  one  were  to 
say  latitia  ;  exultation  is  derived  from  the  exterior  signs  of 
inward  delight,  which  appear  outwardly  in  so  far  as  the 
inward  joy  breaks  forth  from  its  bounds;  and  cheerfulness 
is  so  called  from  certain  special  signs  and  effects  of  gladness. 
Yet  all  these  names  seem  to  belong  to  joy;  for  we  do  not 
employ  them  save  in  speaking  of  rational  beings. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  delight  is  in  the  intellectual  appetite  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 
Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  delight  is  not  in  the  intellectual 
appetite.     Because   the   Philosopher   says    {Rhet.  xi.)  that 


362  QUESTION  XXXI 

delight  is  a  sensible  movement.  But  sensible  movement  is 
not  in  an  intellectual  power.  Therefore  delight  is  not  in 
the  intellectual  appetite. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  delight  is  a  passion.  But  every  passion 
is  in  the  sensitive  appetite.  Therefore  delight  is  only  in  the 
sensitive  appetite. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  delight  is  common  to  us  and  to  the 
irrational  animals.  Therefore  it  is  not  elsewhere  than  in 
that  power  which  we  have  in  common  with  irrational 
animals. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  xxxvi.  4):  Delight  in 
the  Lord.  But  the  sensitive  appetite  cannot  reach  to  God; 
only  the  intellectual  appetite  can.  Therefore  delight  can 
be  in  the  intellectual  appetite. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  3),  a  certain  delight 
arises  from  the  apprehension  of  the  reason.  Now  on  the 
reason  apprehending  something,  not  only  the  sensitive  appe- 
tite is  moved,  as  regards  its  application  to  some  particular 
thing,  but  also  the  intellectual  appetite,  which  is  called  the 
will.  And  accordingly,  in  the  intellectual  appetite  or  will 
there  is  that  delight  which  is  called  joy,  but  not  bodily 
delight. 

However,  there  is  this  difference  of  delight  in  either 
power,  that  delight  of  the  sensitive  appetite  is  accompanied 
by  a  bodily  transmutation,  whereas  delight  of  the  intellec- 
tual appetite  is  nothing  but  the  mere  movement  of  the  will. 
Hence  Augustine  says  {De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  that  desire  and  joy 
are  nothing  else  hut  a  volition  of  consent  to  the  things  we  wish. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  In  this  definition  of  the  Philosopher,  he 
uses  the  word  sensible  in  its  wide  acceptation  for  any  kind 
of  perception.  For  he  says  [Ethic,  x.)  that  delight  is  attendant 
upon  every  sense,  as  it  is  also  upon  every  act  of  the  intellect 
and  contemplation. — Or  we  may  say  that  he  is  defining 
delight  of  the  sensitive  appetite. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Delight  has  the  character  of  passion,  proper!}^ 
speaking,  when  accompanied  by  bodily  transmutation.  It 
is  not  thus  in  the  intellectual  appetite,  but  according  to 
simple  movement :  for  thus  it  is  also  in  God  and  the  angels. 


OF  DELIGHT  CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF        363 

Hence  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vii.)  that  God  rejoices 
by  one  simple  act :  and  Dionysius  says  at  the  end  of  De 
Ccel.  Hier.y  that  the  angels  are  not  susceptible  to  our  passible 
delight,  but  rejoice  together  with  God  with  the  gladness  of  in- 
corruption. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  us  there  is  delight,  not  only  in  common 
with  dumb  animals,  but  also  in  common  with  angels. 
Wherefore  Dionysius  says  {ibid.)  that  holy  men  often  take 
part  in  the  angelic  delights.  Accordingly  we  have  delight, 
not  only  in  the  sensitive  appetite,  which  we  have  in  common 
with  dumb  animals,  but  also  in  the  intellectual  appetite, 
which  we  have  in  common  with  the  angels. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  bodily  and  sensible  pleasures  are  greater 
than  spiritual  and  intellectual  pleasures  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  bodily  and  sensible  pleasures 
are  greater  than  spiritual  and  intelligible  pleasures.  For 
all  men  seek  some  pleasure,  according  to  the  Philosopher 
(Ethic.  X.).  But  more  seek  sensible  pleasures,  than  intelli- 
gible spiritual  pleasures.  Therefore  bodily  pleasures  are 
greater. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  greatness  of  a  cause  is  known  by  its 
effect.  But  bodily  pleasures  have  greater  effects;  since 
they  alter  the  state  of  the  body,  and  in  some  they  cause  madness 
(Ethic,  vii.).     Therefore  bodily  pleasures  are  greater. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  bodily  pleasures  need  to  be  tempered 
and  checked,  by  reason  of  their  vehemence:  whereas  there 
is  no  need  to  check  spiritual  pleasures.  Therefore  bodily 
pleasures  are  greater. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  cxviii.  103) :  How  sweet 
are  Thy  words  to  my  palate  ;  more  than  honey  to  my  mouth  ! 
And  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  x.)  that  the  greatest  pleasure 
is  derived  from  the  operation  of  wisdom. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  pleasure  arises  from 
union  with  a  suitable  object  perceived  or  known.     Now,  in 


364  QUESTION  XXXI 

the  operations  of  the  soul,  especially  of  the  sensitive  and 
intellectual  soul,  it  must  be  noted,  that,  since  they  do  not 
pass  into  outward  matter,  they  are  acts  or  perfections  of 
the  agent,  e.g.,  to  understand,  to  feel,  to  will,  and  the  like: 
because  actions  which  pass  into  outward  matter,  are  actions 
and  perfections  rather  of  the  matter  transformed ;  for  move- 
ment is  the  act  produced  by  the  mover  in  the  thing  moved 
(Phys.  iii) .  x\ccordingly  the  aforesaid  actions  of  the  sensitive 
and  intellectual  soul,  are  themselves  a  certain  good  of  the 
agent,  and  are  known  by  sense  and  intellect.  Wherefore 
from  them  also  does  pleasure  arise,  and  not  only  from  their 
objects. 

If  therefore  we  compare  intellectual  pleasures  with  sen- 
sible pleasures,  according  as  we  delight  in  the  very  actions, 
for  instance  in  sensitive  and  in  intellectual  knowledge; 
without  doubt  intellectual  pleasures  are  much  greater  than 
sensible  pleasures.  For  man  takes  much  more  delight  in 
knowing  something,  by  understanding  it,  than  in  knowing 
something  by  perceiving  it  with  his  sense.  Because  intellec- 
tual knowledge  is  more  perfect;  and  because  it  is  better 
known,  since  the  intellect  reflects  on  its  own  act  more  than 
sense  does.  Moreover  intellectual  knowledge  is  more  be- 
loved: for  there  is  no  one  who  would  not  forfeit  his  bodily 
sight  rather  than  his  intellectual  vision,  as  beasts  or  fools 
are  deprived  thereof,  as  Augustine  says  in  De  Civ.  Dei  {De 
Trin.  xiv.). 

If,  however,  intellectual  spiritual  pleasures  be  compared 
with  sensible  bodily  pleasures,  then,  in  themselves  and 
absolutely  speaking,  spiritual  pleasures  are  greater.  And 
this  appears  from  the  consideration  of  the  three  things 
needed  for  pleasure,  viz.,  the  good  which  is  brought  into 
conjunction,  that  to  which  it  is  conjoined,  and  the  conjunc- 
tion itself.  For  spiritual  good  is  both  greater  and  more 
beloved  than  bodily  good :  a  sign  whereof  is  that  men  abstain 
from  even  the  greatest  bodily  pleasures,  rather  than  suffer 
loss  of  honour  which  is  an  intellectual  good. — ^Likewise  the 
intellectual  faculty  is  much  more  noble  and  more  knowing 
than  the  sensitive  faculty. — -Also  the  conjunction  is  more 


OF  DELIGHT  CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF        365 

intimate,  more  perfect  and  more  firm.  More  intimate, 
because  the  senses  stop  at  the  outward  accidents  of  a  thing, 
whereas  the  intellect  penetrates  to  the  essence;  for  the 
object  of  the  intellect  is  what  a  thing  is.  More  perfect, 
because  the  conjunction  of  the  sensible  to  the  sense  implies 
movement,  which  is  an  imperfect  act:  wherefore  sensible 
pleasures  are  not  perceived  all  at  once,  but  some  part  of 
them  is  passing  away,  while  some  other  part  is  looked  for- 
ward to  as  yet  to  be  realized,  as  is  manifest  in  pleasures  of  the 
table  and  in  sexual  pleasures :  whereas  intelligible  things  are 
without  movement :  hence  pleasures  of  this  kind  are  realized 
all  at  once.  More  firm;  because  the  objects  of  bodily 
pleasure  are  corruptible,  and  soon  pass  away;  whereas 
spiritual  goods  are  incorruptible. 

On  the  other  hand,  in  relation  to  us,  bodily  pleasures  are 
more  vehement,  for  three  reasons.  First,  because  sensible 
things  are  more  known  to  us,  than  intelligible  things. — • 
Secondly,  because  sensible  pleasures,  through  being  passions 
of  the  sensitive  appetite,  are  accompanied  by  some  alteration 
in  the  body:  whereas  this  does  not  occur  in  spiritual 
pleasures,  save  by  reason  of  a  certain  reaction  of  the  superior 
appetite  on  the  lower. — -Thirdly,  because  bodily  pleasures 
are  sought  as  remedies  for  bodily  defects  or  troubles,  whence 
various  griefs  arise.  Wherefore  bodily  pleasures,  by  reason 
of  their  succeeding  griefs  of  this  kind,  are  felt  the  more,  and 
consequently  are  more  acceptable  than  spiritual  pleasures, 
which  have  no  contrary  griefs,  as  we  shall  state  farther  on 
(Q.  XXXV.,  A.  5). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  reason  why  more  seek  bodily  pleasures 
is  because  sensible  goods  are  known  better  and  more  gener- 
ally: and,  again,  because  men  need  pleasures  as  remedies 
for  many  kinds  of  sorrow  and  sadness :  and  since  the  majority 
cannot  attain  spiritual  pleasures,  which  are  proper  to  the 
virtuous,  hence  it  is  that  they  turn  aside  to  seek  those  of 
the  body. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Bodily  transmutation  arises  more  from 
bodily  pleasures,  inasmuch  as  they  are  passions  of  the 
sensitive  appetite. 


366  QUESTION  XXXI 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Bodily  pleasures  are  realized  in  the  sen- 
sitive faculty  which  is  governed  by  reason:  wherefore  they 
need  to  be  tempered  and  checked  by  reason.  But  spiritual 
pleasures  are  perceived  by  the  mind,  which  is  itself  the 
rule:  wherefore  they  are  in  themselves  both  sober  and 
moderate. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  the  pleasures  of  touch  are  greater   than 
the  pleasures  afforded  by  the  other  senses  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  pleasures  of  touch  are  not 
greater  than  the  pleasures  afforded  by  the  other  senses. 
Because  the  greatest  pleasure  seems  to  be  that  without 
which  all  joy  is  at  an  end.  But  such  is  the  pleasure  afforded 
by  the  sight,  according  to  the  words  of  Tobias  v.  12 :  What 
manner  of  joy  shall  he  to  me,  who  sit  in  darkness,  and  see  not 
the  light  of  heaven  ?  Therefore  the  pleasure  afforded  by  the 
sight  is  the  greatest  of  sensible  pleasures. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  every  one  finds  pleasure  in  what  he  loves, 
as  the  Philosopher  says  (Rhet.  i.).  But  of  all  the  senses  the 
sight  is  loved  most  (Metaph.  i.).  Therefore  the  greatest 
pleasure  is  that  which  is  afforded  by  the  sight. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  beginning  of  friendship  which  is  for 
the  sake  of  the  pleasant  is  principally  sight.  But  pleasure 
is  the  cause  of  such  friendship.  Therefore  the  greatest 
pleasure  seems  to  be  afforded  by  sight. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.)  that  the 
greatest  pleasures  are  those  which  are  afforded  by  the 
touch. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXV.,  A.  2  ad  1; 
Q.  XXVII.,  A.  4  ad  i),  everything  gives  pleasure  according 
as  it  is  loved.  Now,  as  stated  in  Metaph.  i.,  the  senses  are 
loved  for  two  reasons :  for  the  purpose  of  knowledge,  and  on 
account  of  their  usefulness.  Wherefore  the  senses  afford 
pleasure  in  both  these  ways.  But  because  it  is  proper  to  man 
to  apprehend  knowledge  itself  as  something  good ;  it  follows 
that  the  former  pleasures  of   the  senses,  i.e.,  those  which 


OF  DELIGHT  CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF        367 

arise  from  knowledge,  are  proper  to  man :  whereas  pleasures 
of  the  senses,  as  loved  for  their  usefulness,  are  common 
to  all  animals. 

If  therefore  we  speak  of  that  sensible  pleasure  which  is 
by  reason  of  knowledge,  it  is  evident  that  the  sight  affords 
greater  pleasure  than  any  other  sense. — -On  the  other  hand, 
if  we  speak  of  that  sensible  pleasure  which  is  by  reason  of 
usefulness,  then  the  greatest  pleasure  is  afforded  by  the 
touch.  For  the  usefulness  of  the  senses  is  gauged  by  their 
relation  to  the  preservation  of  the  animal's  nature.  Now 
the  sensible  objects  of  touch  bear  the  closest  relation  to 
this  usefulness:  for  the  touch  takes  cognizance  of  those 
things  of  which  an  animal  consists — namely,  of  things  hot 
and  cold  and  the  like.  Wherefore  in  this  respect,  the 
pleasures  of  touch,  are  greater  as  being  more  closely  related 
to  the  end.  For  this  reason,  too,  other  animals  who  do  not 
experience  sensible  pleasure  save  by  reason  of  usefulness, 
derive  no  pleasure  from  the  other  senses  except  as  sub- 
ordinated to  the  sensible  objects  of  the  touch: /or  dogs  do 
not  take  delight  in  the  smell  of  hares,  hut  in  eating  them  ;  .  .  . 
nor  does  the  lion  feel  pleasure  in  the  lowing  of  an  ox,  hut  in 
devouring  it  {Ethic,  iii.). 

Since  then  the  pleasure  afforded  by  touch  is  the  greatest 
in  respect  of  usefulness,  and  the  pleasure  afforded  by  sight, 
the  greatest  in  respect  of  knowledge;  if  anyone  wish  to 
compare  these  two,  he  will  find  that  the  pleasure  of  touch 
is,  absolutely  speaking,  greater  than  the  pleasure  of  sight, 
so  far  as  the  latter  remains  within  the  limits  of  sensible 
pleasure.  Because  it  is  evident  that  in  everything,  that 
which  is  natural  is  most  powerful :  and  it  is  to  these 
pleasures  of  the  touch  that  the  natural  concupiscences, 
such  as  those  of  food,  sexual  union,  and  the  like,  are  ordained. 
— If,  however,  we  consider  the  pleasures  of  sight,  inasmuch 
as  sight  is  the  handmaid  of  the  mind,  then  the  pleasures 
of  sight  are  greater,  forasmuch  as  intellectual  pleasures  are 
greater  than  sensible. 

Reply  Ob]'.  1. — Joy,  as  stated  above  (A.  3),  denotes 
animal    pleasure;    and    this    belongs    principally    to    the 


368  QUESTION  XXXI 

sight.  But  natural  pleasure  belongs  principally  to  the 
touch. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  sight  is  loved  most,  on  account  of  know- 
ledge, because  it  helps-  us  to  distinguish  many  things  as  is 
stated  in  the  same  passage  (Metaph.  i.). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Pleasure  causes  carnal  love  in  one  way;  the 
sight,  in  another.  For  pleasure,  especially  that  which  is 
afforded  by  the  touch,  is  the  final  cause  of  the  friendship 
which  is  for  the  sake  of  the  pleasant :  whereas  the  sight  is  a 
cause  like  that  from  which  a  movement  has  its  beginning, 
inasmuch  as  the  beholder  on  seeing  the  lovable  object  re- 
ceives an  impression  of  its  image,  which  entices  him  to  love 
it  and  to  seek  its  delight. 

Seventh  Article, 
whether  any  pleasure  is  not  natural  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  no  pleasure  is  not  natural. 
For  pleasure  is  to  the  emotions  of  the  soul  what  repose  is 
to  bodies.  But  the  appetite  of  a  natural  body  does  not 
repose  save  in  a  connatural  place.  Neither,  therefore,  can 
the  repose  of  the  animal  appetite,  which  is  pleasure,  be 
elsewhere  than  in  something  connatural.  Therefore  no 
pleasure  is  non-natural. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  what  is  against  nature  is  violent.  But 
whatever  is  violent  causes  grief  {Metaph.  v.)  Therefore 
nothing  which  is  unnatural  can  give  pleasure. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  fact  of  being  established  in  one's 
own  nature,  if  perceived,  gives  rise  to  pleasure,  as  is  evident 
from  the  Philosopher's  definition  quoted  above  (A.  i). 
But  it  is  natural  to  every  thing  to  be  established  in  its  nature ; 
because  natural  movement  tends  to  a  natural  end.  There- 
fore every  pleasure  is  natural. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  vii.)  that 
some  things  are  pleasant  not  from  nature  but  from  disease. 

I  answer  that,  We  speak  of  that  as  being  natural,  which 
is  in  accord  with  nature,  as  stated  in  Phys.  ii.     Now,  in 


OF  DELIGHT  CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF        369 

man,  nature  can  be  taken  in  two  ways.  First,  inasmuch 
as  intellect  and  reason  is  the  principal  part  of  man's  nature, 
since  in  respect  thereof  he  has  his  own  specific  nature. 
And  in  this  sense,  those  pleasures  may  be  called  natural  to 
man,  which  are  derived  from  things  pertaining  to  man  in 
respect  of  his  reason:  for  instance,  it  is  natural  to  man  to 
take  pleasure  in  contemplating  the  truth  and  in  doing  works 
of  virtue. — -Secondly,  nature  in  man  may  be  taken  as  con- 
trasted with  reason,  and  as  denoting  that  which  is  common 
to  man  and  other  animals,  especially  that  part  of  man  which 
does  not  obey  reason.  And  in  this  sense,  that  which  per- 
tains to  the  preservation  of  the  body,  either  as  regards  the 
individual,  as  food,  drink,  sleep,  and  the  like,  or  as  regards 
the  species,  as  sexual  intercourse,  are  said  to  afford  man 
natural  pleasure.  Under  each  kind  of  pleasures,  we  find 
some  that  are  not  natural  speaking  absolutely,  and  yet  con- 
natural in  some  respect.  For  it  happens  in  an  individual 
that  some  one  of  the  natural  principles  of  the  species  is 
corrupted,  so  that  something  which  is  contrary  to  the  specific 
nature,  becomes  accidentally  natural  to  this  individual: 
thus  it  is  natural  to  this  hot  water  to  give  heat.  Conse- 
quently it  happens  that  something  which  is  not  natural  to 
man,  either  in  regard  to  reason,  or  in  regard  to  the  preserva- 
tion of  the  body,  becomes  connatural  to  this  individual 
man,  on  account  of  there  being  some  corruption  of  nature 
in  him.  And  this  corruption  may  be  either  on  the  part  of 
the  body, — from  some  ailment ;  thus  to  a  man  suffering  from 
fever,  sweet  things  seem  bitter,  and  vice  versa, — or  from  an 
evil  temperament;  thus  some  take  pleasure  in  eating  earth 
and  coals  {Ethic,  v.)  and  the  like;  or  on  the  part  of  the  soul; 
thus  from  custom  some  take  pleasure  in  cannibalism  or  in 
the  unnatural  intercourse  of  man  and  beast,  or  other  such- 
like things,  which  are  not  in  accord  with  human  nature. 
This  suffices  for  the  answers  to  the  objections. 


II.  I  24 


37^  QUESTION  XXXI 


Eighth  Article, 
whether  one  pleasure  can  be  contrary  to 

ANOTHER  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  one  pleasure  cannot  be  con- 
trary to  another.  Because  the  passions  of  the  soul  derive 
their  species  and  contrariety  from  their  objects.  Now  the 
object  of  pleasure  is  the  good.  Since  therefore  good  is  not 
contrary  to  good,  but  good  is  contrary  to  evil,  and  evil  to 
evil,  as  stated  in  Prcedic.  viii.;  it  seems  that  one  pleasure  is 
not  contrary  to  another. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  to  one  thing  there  is  one  contrary,  as 
is  proved  in  Metaph.  x.  But  sadness  is  contrary  to  pleasure. 
Therefore  pleasure  is  not  contrary  to  pleasure. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  one  pleasure  is  contrary  to  another, 
this  is  only  on  account  of  the  contrariety  of  the  things  which 
give  pleasure.  But  this  difference  is  material:  whereas 
contrariety  is  a  difference  of  form,  as  stated  in  Metaph.  x. 
Therefore  there  is  no  contrariety  between  one  pleasure  and 
another. 

On  the  contrary.  Things  of  the  same  genus  that  impede 
one  another  are  contraries.  But  some  pleasures  impede 
one  another,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  x.  Therefore  some  pleasures 
are  contrary  to  one  another. 

/  answer  that.  Pleasure,  in  the  emotions  of  the  soul,  is 
likened  to  repose  in  natural  bodies,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXIII.,  A.  4).  Now  one  repose  is  said  to  be  contrary 
to  another  when  they  are  in  contrary  termini;  thus  repose 
in  a  high  place  is  contrary  to  repose  in  a  low  place  (Phys.  v.). 
Wherefore  it  happens  in  the  emotions  of  the  soul  that  one 
pleasure  is  contrary  to  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  i .  This  saying  of  the  Philosopher  is  to  be  under- 
stood of  good  and  evil  as  applied  to  virtues  and  vices:  be- 
cause one  vice  may  be  contrary  to  another  vice,  whereas 
no  virtue  can  be  contrary  to  another  virtue.  But  in  other 
things  nothing  prevents  one  good  being  contrary  to  another, 


OF  DELIGHT  CONSIDERED  IN  ITSELF        371 

such  as  hot  and  cold,  of  which  the  former  is  good  in  relation 
to  fire,  the  latter,  in  relation  to  water.  And  in  this  way  one 
pleasure  can  be  contrary  to  another. — That  this  is  im- 
possible with  regard  to  the  good  of  virtue,  is  due  to  the  fact 
that  virtue's  good  depends  on  fittingness  in  relation  to  some 
one  thing — i.e.,  the  reason. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Pleasure,  in  the  emotions  of  the  soul,  is 
likened  to  natural  repose  in  bodies:  because  its  object  is 
something  suitable  and  connatural,  so  to  speak.  But 
sadness  is  like  a  violent  repose:  because  its  object  is  dis- 
agreeable to  the  animal  appetite,  just  as  the  place  of  violent 
repose  is  disagreeable  to  the  natural  appetite.  Now  natural 
repose  is  contrary  both  to  violent  repose  of  the  same  body, 
and  to  the  natural  repose  of  another,  as  stated  in  Phys.  v. 
Wherefore  pleasure  is  contrary  both  to  another  pleasure  and 
to  sadness. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  things  in  which  we  take  pleasure, 
since  they  are  the  objects  of  pleasure,  cause  not  only  a 
material,  but  also  a  formal  difference,  if  the  formality  of 
pleasureableness  be  different.  Because  difference  in  the 
formal  object  causes  a  specific  difference  in  acts  and  pas- 
sions, as  stated  above  (Q.  XXIII.,  AA.  i,  4;  Q.  XXX.  A.  2). 


QUESTION  XXXII. 

OF  THE  CAUSE  OF  PLEASURE. 

[In  Eight  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  causes  of  pleasure:  and  under 
this  head  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether 
operation  is  the  proper  cause  of  pleasure  ?  (2)  Whether 
movement  is  a  cause  of  pleasure  ?  (3)  Whether  hope  and 
memory  cause  pleasure  ?  (4)  Whether  sadness  causes 
pleasure  ?  (5)  Whether  the  actions  of  others  are  a  cause  of 
pleasure  to  us  ?  (6)  Whether  doing  good  to  another  is  a 
cause  of  pleasure  ?  (7)  Whether  likeness  is  a  cause  of 
pleasure  ?     (8)  Whether  wonder  is  a  cause  of  pleasure  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  operation  is  the  proper  cause  of 
pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  operation  is  not  the  proper  and 
first  cause  of  pleasure.  For,  as  the  Philosopher  says 
(Rhet.  i.),  pleasure  consists  in  a  perception  of  the  senses,  since 
knowledge  is  requisite  for  pleasure,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXXI.,  A.  i).  But  the  objects  of  operations  are 
knowable  before  the  operations  themselves.  Therefore 
operation  is  not  the  proper  cause  of  pleasure. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  pleasure  consists  especially  in  an  end 
gained:  since  it  is  this  that  is  chiefly  desired.  But  the  end 
is  not  always  an  operation,  but  is  sometimes  the  effect  of 
the  operation.  Therefore  operation  is  not  the  proper  and 
direct  cause  of  pleasure. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  leisure  and  rest  consist  in  cessation  from 

372 


OF  THE  CAUSE  OF  PLEASURE  373 

work:  and  they  are  objects  of  pleasure  (Rhet.  i.).  Therefore 
operation  is  not  the  proper  cause  of  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  vii.,  x.)  that 
pleasure  is  a  connatural  and  uninterrupted  operation. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXXI.,  A.  i),  two 
things  are  requisite  for  pleasure:  namely,  the  attainment 
of  the  suitable  good,  and  knowledge  of  this  attainment. 
Now  each  of  these  consists  in  a  kind  of  operation:  because 
actual  knowledge  is  an  operation;  and  the  attainment  of 
the  suitable  good  is  by  means  of  an  operation.  Moreover, 
the  proper  operation  itself  is  a  suitable  good.  Wherefore 
every  pleasure  must  needs  be  the  result  of  some  operation. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  objects  of  operations  are  not  pleasur- 
able save  inasmuch  as  they  are  united  to  us;  either  by 
knowledge  alone,  as  when  we  take  pleasure  in  thinking  of 
or  looking  at  certain  things ;  or  in  some  other  way  in  addition 
to  knowledge;  as  when  a  man  takes  pleasure  in  knowing 
that  he  has  something  good, — -riches,  honour,  or  the  like; 
which  would  not  be  pleasurable  unless  they  were  appre- 
hended as  possessed.  For  as  the  Philosopher  observes 
(Polit.  ii.)  we  take  great  pleasure  in  looking  upon  a  thing  as 
our  own,  by  reason  of  the  natural  love  we  have  for  ourselves. 
Now  to  have  suchlike  things  is  nothing  else  but  to  use 
them  or  to  be  able  to  use  them:  and  this  is  through  some 
operation.  Wherefore  it  is  evident  that  every  pleasure  is 
traced  to  some  operation  as  its  cause. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Even  when  it  is  not  an  operation,  but  the 
effect  of  an  operation,  that  is  the  end,  this  effect  is  pleasant 
in  so  far  as  possessed  or  effected:  and  this  implies  use  or 
operation. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Operations  are  pleasant,  in  so  far  as  they  are 
proportionate  and  connatural  to  the  agent.  Now,  since 
human  power  is  finite,  operation  is  proportionate  thereto 
according  to  a  certain  measure.  Wherefore  if  it  exceed  that 
measure,  it  will  be  no  longer  proportionate  or  pleasant,  but, 
on  the  contrary,  painful  and  irksome.  And  in  this  sense, 
leisure  and  play  and  other  things  pertaining  to  repose, 
are  pleasant,  inasmuch  as  they  banish  sadness  which  results 
from  labour. 


374  QUESTION  XXXII 

Second  Article, 
whether  movement  is  a  cause  of  pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  movement  is  not  a  cause  ol 
pleasure.  Because,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXI.,  A.  i),  the 
good  which  is  obtained  and  is  actually  possessed,  is  the  cause 
of  pleasure:  wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  viii.) 
that  pleasure  is  not  compared  with  generation,  but  with 
the  operation  of  a  thing  already  in  existence.  Now  that 
which  is  being  moved  towards  something  has  it  not  as  yet ; 
but,  so  to  speak,  is  being  generated  in  its  regard,  for  as 
much  as  generation  or  corruption  are  united  to  every 
movement,  as  stated  in  Phys.  viii.  Therefore  movement  is 
not  a  cause  of  pleasure. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  movement  is  the  chief  cause  of  toil  and 
fatigue  in  our  works.  But  operations  through  being  toil- 
some and  fatiguing  are  not  pleasant  but  disagreeable. 
Therefore  movement  is  not  a  cause  of  pleasure. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  movement  implies  a  certain  innova- 
tion, which  is  the  opposite  of  custom.  But  things  which 
we  are  accustomed  to,  are  pleasant,  as  the  Philosopher 
says  (Rhet.  i.).  Therefore  movement  is  not  a  cause  of 
pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Conf.  viii.):  What  means 
this,  0  Lord  my  God,  whereas  Thou  art  everlasting  joy  to 
Thyself,  and  some  things  around  Thee  evermore  rejoice  in 
Thee  ?  What  means  this,  that  this  portion  of  things  ebbs 
and  -flows  alternately  displeased  and  reconciled  ?  From  these 
words  we  gather  that  man  rejoices  and  takes  pleasure  in 
some  kind  of  alternations:  and  therefore  movement  seems 
to  cause  pleasure. 

/  answer  that.  Three  things  are  requisite  for  pleasure; 
two,  i.e.,  the  one  that  is  pleased  and  the  pleasurable  object 
conjoined  to  him;  and  a  third,  which  is  knowledge  of  this 
conjunction:  and  in  respect  of  these  three,  movement  is 
pleasant,  as  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  vii.  and  Rhet.  i.). 


OF  THE  CAUSE  OF  PLEASURE      375 

For  as  far  as  we  who  feel  pleasure  are  concerned,  change  is 
pleasant  to  us  because  our  nature  is  changeable;  for  which 
reason  that  which  is  suitable  to  us  at  one  time  is  not  suitable 
at  another, — thus  to  warm  himself  at  a  fire  is  suitable  to 
man  in  winter  and  not  in  summer. — Again,  on  the  part  of 
the  pleasing  good  which  is  united  to  us,  change  is  pleasant. 
Because  the  continued  action  of  an  agent  increases  its  effect : 
thus  the  longer  a  person  remains  near  the  fire,  the  more  he 
is  warmed  and  dried.  Now  the  natural  mode  of  being 
consists  in  a  certain  measure:  and  therefore  when  the  con- 
tinued presence  of  a  pleasant  object  exceeds  the  measure 
of  one's  natural  mode  of  being,  the  removal  of  that  object 
becomes  pleasant. — ^On  the  part  of  the  knowledge  itself 
(change  becomes  pleasant),  because  man  desires  to  know 
something  whole  and  perfect :  when  therefore  a  thing  cannot 
be  apprehended  all  at  once  as  a  whole,  change  in  such  a 
thing  is  pleasant,  so  that  one  part  may  pass  and  another 
succeed,  and  thus  the  whole  be  perceived.  Hence  Augus- 
tine says  [Conf.  iv.) :  Thou  wouldst  not  have  the  syllables 
stay,  hut  fly  away,  that  ■  others  may  come,  and  thou  hear 
the  whole.  And  so  whenever  any  one  thing  is  made  up  of 
many,  all  of  which  do  not  exist  together,  all  would  please 
collectively  more  than  they  do  severally,  if  all  could  he  perceived 
collectively. 

li  therefore  there  be  any  thing,  whose  nature  is  unchange- 
able; the  natural  mode  of  whose  being  cannot  be  exceeded 
by  the  continuation  of  any  pleasing  object;  and  which  can 
behold  the  whole  object  of  its  delight  at  once, — -to  such  a 
one  change  will  afford  no  delight.  And  the  more  any 
pleasures  approach  to  this,  the  more  are  they  capable  of 
being  continual. 

Reply  Ob],  i.  Although  the  subject  of  movement  has  not 
yet  perfectly  that  to  which  it  is  moved,  nevertheless  it  is 
beginning  to  have  something  thereof:  and  in  this  respect 
movement  itself  has  something  of  pleasure.  But  it  falls 
short  of  the  perfection  of  pleasure ;  because  the  more  perfect 
pleasures  regard  things  that  are  unchangeable. — Moreover 
movement  becomes  the  cause  of  pleasure,  in  so  far  as  thereby 


376  QUESTION  XXXTI 

something  which  previously  was  unsuitable,  becomes  suit- 
able or  ceases  to  be,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Movement  causes  toil  and  fatigue,  when  it 
exceeds  our  natural  aptitude.  It  is  not  thus  that  it  causes 
pleasure,  but  by  removing  the  obstacles  to  our  natural 
aptitude. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  What  is  customary  becomes  pleasant,  in 
so  far  as  it  becomes  natural :  because  custom  is  like  a  second 
nature.  But  the  movement  which  gives  pleasure  is  not 
that  which  departs  from  custom,  but  rather  that  which 
prevents  the  corruption  of  the  natural  mode  of  being,  that 
might  result  from  continued  operation.  And  thus  from 
the  same  cause  of  connaturalness,  both  custom  and  move- 
ment become  pleasant. 

Third  Article, 
whether  hope  and  memory  cause  pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  memory  and  hope  do  not  cause 
pleasure.  Because  pleasure  is  caused  by  present  good,  as 
Damascene  says  {De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.).  But  hope  and 
memory  regard  what  is  absent:  since  memory  is  of  the 
past,  and  hope,  of  the  future.  Therefore  memory  and  hope 
do  not  cause  pleasure. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  same  thing  is  not  the  cause  of  con- 
traries. But  hope  causes  affliction,  according  to  Pro  v. 
xiii.  12 :  Hope  that  is  deferred  afflicteth  the  soul.  Therefore 
hope  does  not  cause  pleasure. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  just  as  hope  agrees  with  pleasure  in  re- 
garding good,  so  also  do  desire  and  love.  Therefore  hope 
should  not  be  assigned  as  a  cause  of  pleasure,  any  more  than 
desire  or  love. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Rom.  xii.  12) :  Rejoicing  in 
hope  ;  and  (Ps.  Ixxvi.  4) :  I  rememhered  God,  and  was  de- 
lighted. 

I  answer  that,  Pleasure  is  caused  by  the  presence  of  suit- 
able good,  in  so  far  as  it  is  felt,  or  perceived  in  any  way. 


OF  THE  CAUSE  OF  PLEASURE  377 

Now  a  thing  is  present  to  us  in  two  ways.  First,  in  know- 
ledge— i.e.,  according  as  the  thing  known  is  in  the  knower 
by  its  hkeness;  secondly,  in  reality — i.e.,  according  as  one 
thing  is  in  real  conjunction  of  any  kind  with  another,  either 
actually  or  potentially.  And  since  real  conjunction  is 
greater  than  conjunction  by  likeness,  which  is  the  conjunc- 
tion of  knowledge:  and  again,  since  actual  is  greater  than 
potential  conjunction:  therefore  the  greatest  pleasure  is 
that  which  arises  from  sensation  which  requires  the  presence 
of  the  sensible  object.  The  second  place  belongs  to  the 
pleasure  of  hope,  wherein  there  is  pleasurable  conjunction, 
not  only  in  respect  of  apprehension,  but  also  in  respect  of 
the  faculty  or  power  of  obtaining  the  pleasurable  object. 
The  third  place  belongs  to  the  pleasure  of  memory,  which 
has  only  the  conjunction  of  apprehension. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Hope  and  memory  are  indeed  of  things 
which,  absolutely  speaking,  are  absent:  and  yet  these  are, 
after  a  fashion,  present,  i.e.,  either  according  to  apprehen- 
sion only;  or  according  to  apprehension  and  possibility,  at 
least  supposed,  of  attainment. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Nothing  prevents  the  same  thing,  in  different 
ways,  being  the  cause  of  contraries.  And  so  hope,  inas- 
much as  it  implies  a  present  appraising  of  a  future  good, 
causes  pleasure;  whereas,  inasmuch  as  it  implies  absence  of 
that  good,  it  causes  affliction. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Love  and  concupiscence  also  cause  pleasure. 
For  everything  that  is  loved  becomes  pleasing  to  the  lover, 
since  love  is  a  kind  of  union  or  connaturalness  of  lover  and 
beloved.  In  like  manner  every  object  of  desire  is  pleasing 
to  the  one  that  desires,  since  desire  is  chiefly  a  craving  for 
pleasure.  However  hope,  as  implying  a  certainty  of  the 
real  presence  of  the  pleasing  good,  that  is  not  implied  either 
by  love  or  by  concupiscence,  is  reckoned  in  preference  to 
them  as  causing  pleasure ;  and  also  in  preference  to  memory, 
which  is  of  that  which  has  already  passed  away. 


378  QUESTION  XXXII 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  sadness  causes  pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  sadness  does  not  cause  pleasure. 
For  nothing  causes  its  own  contrary.  But  sadness  is  con- 
trary to  pleasure.     Therefore  it  does  not  cause  it. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  contraries  have  contrary  effects.  But 
pleasures,  when  called  to  mind,  cause  pleasure.  Therefore 
sad  things,  when  remembered,  cause  sorrow  and  not  pleasure. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  as  sadness  is  to  pleasure,  so  is  hatred  to 
love.  But  hatred  does  not  cause  love,  but  rather  the  other 
way  about.     Therefore  sadness  does  not  cause  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  xli.  4) :  My  tears  have  been 
my  bread  day  and  night :  where  bread  denotes  the  refresh- 
ment of  pleasure.  Therefore  tears,  which  arise  from  sadness, 
can  give  pleasure. 

I  answer  that,  Sadness  may  be  considered  in  two  ways :  as 
existing  actually,  and  as  existing  in  the  memory:  and  in 
both  ways  sadness  can  cause  pleasure.  Because  sadness, 
as  actually  existing,  causes  pleasure,  inasmuch  as  it  brings 
to  mind  that  which  is  loved,  the  absence  of  which  causes 
sadness;  and  yet  the  mere  thought  of  it  gives  pleasure. — 
The  recollection  of  sadness  becomes  a  cause  of  pleasure,  on 
account  of  the  deliverance  which  ensued:  because  absence 
of  evil  is  looked  upon  as  something  good ;  wherefore  so  far 
as  a  man  thinks  that  he  has  been  delivered  from  that  which 
caused  him  sorrow  and  pain,  so  much  reason  has  he  to  re- 
joice. Hence  Augustine  says  in  De  Civ.  Dei  xxii  (Gregory,— 
Moral  iv.)  that  oftentimes  in  joy  we  call  to  mind  sad  things  .  .  . 
and  in  the  season  of  health  we  recall  past  pains  without  feeling 
pain,  .  .  .  and  in  proportion  are  the  more  filled  with  joy  and 
gladness  :  and  again  (Conf.  viii.)  he  says  that  the  more  peril 
there  was  in  the  battle,  so  much  the  more  joy  will  there  be  in  the 
triumph. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Sometimes  accidentally  a  thing  is  the  cause 
of  its  contrary :  thus  that  which  is  cold  sometimes  causes  heat, 


Of  the  cause  of  pleasure  379 

as  stated  in  Phys.  viii.  In  like  manner  sadness  is  the  acci- 
dental cause  of  pleasure,  in  so  far  as  it  gives  rise  to  the 
apprehension  of  something  pleasant. 

Refly  Ohj.  2.  Sad  things,  called  to  mind,  cause  pleasure, 
not  in  so  far  as  they  are  sad  and  contrary  to  pleasant  things ; 
but  in  so  far  as  man  is  delivered  from  them.  In  like  manner 
the  recollection  of  pleasant  things,  by  reason  of  these  being 
lost,  may  cause  sadness. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Hatred  also  can  be  the  accidental  cause  of 
love:  i.e.,  so  far  as  some  love  one  another, inasmuch  as  they 
agree  in  hating  one  and  the  same  thing. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  the  actions  of  others  are  a  cause  of 
pleasure  to  us  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  actions  of  others  are  not  a 
cause  of  pleasure  to  us.  Because  the  cause  of  pleasure  is 
our  own  good  when  conjoined  to  us.  But  the  actions  of 
others  are  not  conjoined  to  us.  Therefore  they  are  not  a 
cause  of  pleasure  to  us. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  action  is  the  agent's  own  good.  If, 
therefore,  the  actions  of  others  are  a  cause  of  pleasure  to  us, 
for  the  same  reason  all  goods  belonging  to  others  will  be 
pleasing  to  us:  which  is  evidently  untrue. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  action  is  pleasant  through  proceeding 
from  an  innate  habit;  hence  it  is  stated  in  Ethic,  ii.  that 
we  must  reckon  the  pleasure  which  follows  after  action,  as 
heing  the  sign  of  a  habit  existing  in  us.  But  the  actions  of 
others  do  not  proceed  from  habits  existing  in  us,  but,  some- 
times, from  habits  existing  in  the  agents.  Therefore  the 
actions  of  others  are  not  pleasing  to  us,  but  to  the  agents 
themselves. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  in  the  second  canonical 
epistle  of  John  {verse  4):  /  was  exceeding  glad  that  I  found 
thy  children  walking  in  truth. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i;  Q.  XXXI. ,  A.  i), 


38o  QUESTION  XXXII 

two  things  are  requisite  for  pleasure,  namely,  the  attainment 
of  one's  proper  good,  and  the  knowledge  of  having  obtained 
it.  Wherefore  the  action  of  another  may  cause  pleasure 
to  us  in  three  ways.  First,  from  the  fact  that  we  obtain 
some  good  through  the  action  of  another.  And  in  this  way, 
the  actions  of  those  who  do  some  good  to  us,  are  pleasing  to 
us:  since  it  is  pleasant  to  be  benefited  by  another. — 
Secondly,  from  the  fact  that  another's  action  makes  us  to 
know  or  appreciate  our  own  good:  and  for  this  reason  men 
take  pleasure  in  being  praised  or  honoured  by  others,  be- 
cause, to  wit,  they  thus  become  aware  of  some  good  existing 
in  themselves.  And  since  this  appreciation  receives  greater 
weight  from  the  testimony  of  good  and  wise  men,  hence  men 
take  greater  pleasure  in  being  praised  and  honoured  by  them. 
And  because  a  flatterer  is  one  who  praises  openly,  therefore 
flattery  is  pleasing  to  some.  And  as  love  is  for  something 
good,  while  admiration  is  for  something  great,  so  it  is 
pleasant  to  be  loved  and  admired  by  others,  inasmuch  as 
a  man  thus  becomes  aware  of  his  own  goodness  or  greatness, 
through  their  giving  pleasure  to  others. — Thirdly,  from  the 
fact  that  another's  actions,  if  they  be  good,  are  reckoned  as 
one's  own  good,  by  reason  of  the  power  of  love,  which  makes 
a  man  to  regard  his  friend  as  one  with  himself.  And  on 
account  of  hatred,  which  makes  one  to  reckon  another's 
good  as  being  in  opposition  to  oneself,  the  evil  action  of  an 
enemy  becomes  an  object  of  pleasure:  whence  it  is  written 
(i  Cor.  xiii.  6)  that  charity  rejoiceth  not  in  iniquity,  hut  re- 
joiceth  with  the  truth. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Another's  action  may  be  conjoined  to  me, 
either  by  its  effect,  as  in  the  first  way;  or  by  knowledge,  as 
in  the  second  way;  or  by  affection,  as  in  the  third  way. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  This  argument  avails  for  the  third  mode, 
but  not  for  the  first  two. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Although  the  actions  of  another  do  not  pro- 
ceed from  habits  that  are  in  me,  yet  they  either  produce 
in  me  something  that  gives  pleasure;  or  they  make  me 
appreciate  or  know  a  habit  of  mine;  or  they  proceed  from 
the  habit  of  one  who  is  united  to  me  by  love. 


OF  THE  CAUSE  OF  PLEASURE       381 


Sixth  Article. 

whether  doing  good  to  another  is  a  cause  of 

pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  doing  good  to  another  is  not  a 
cause  of  pleasure.  Because  pleasure  is  caused  by  one's 
obtaining  one's  proper  good,  as  stated  above  (AA.  i,  5; 
Q.  XXXI.,  A.  i).  But  doing  good  pertains  not  to  the  ob- 
taining but  to  the  spending  of  one's  proper  good.  Therefore 
it  seems  to  be  the  cause  of  sadness  rather  than  of  pleasure. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.)  that 
illiherality  is  more  connatural  to  man  than  prodigality.  Now 
it  is  a  mark  of  prodigality  to  do  good  to  others;  while  it  is 
a  mark  of  illiherality  to  desist  from  doing  good.  Since  there- 
fore everyone  takes  pleasure  in  a  connatural  operation, 
as  stated  in  Ethic,  vii.  and  x.,  it  seems  that  doing  good  to 
others  is  not  a  cause  of  pleasure. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  contrary  effects  proceed  from  contrary 
causes.  But  man  takes  a  natural  pleasure  in  certain  kinds 
of  ill-doing,  such  as  overcoming,  contradicting  or  scolding 
others,  or,  if  he  be  angry,  of  punishing  them,  as  the  Philo- 
sopher says  {Rhet.  i.).  Therefore  doing  good  to  others  is 
a  cause  of  sadness  rather  than  of  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Polit.  ii.)  that  it  is 
most  pleasant  to  give  presents  or  assistance  to  friends  and 
strangers. 

I  answer  that,  Doing  good  to  another  may  give  pleasure 
in  three  ways.  First,  in  consideration  of  the  effect,  which 
is  the  good  conferred  on  another.  In  this  respect,  inasmuch 
as  through  being  united  to  others  by  love,  we  look  upon 
their  good  as  being  our  own,  we  take  pleasure  in  the  good  we 
do  to  others,  especially  to  our  friends,  as  in  our  own  good. — 
Secondly,  in  consideration  of  the  end;  as  when  a  man, 
from  doing  good  to  another,  hopes  to  get  some  good  for 
himself,  either  from  God  or  from  man :  for  hope  is  a  cause  of 
pleasure. — Thirdly,  in  consideration  of  the  principle:  and 


382  QUESTION  XXXII 

thus,  doing  good  to  another,  can  give  pleasure  in  respect  of 
a  threefold  principle.  One  is  the  faculty  of  doing  good: 
and  in  this  regard,  doing  good  to  another  becomes  pleasant, 
in  so  far  as  it  arouses  in  man  an  imagination  of  abundant 
good  existing  in  him,  whereof  he  is  able  to  give  others  a 
share.  Wherefore  men  take  pleasure  in  their  children,  and 
in  their  own  works,  as  being  things  on  which  they  bestow 
a  share  of  their  own  good.  Another  principle  is  a  man's 
habitual  inclination  to  do  good,  by  reason  of  which  doing 
good  becomes  connatural  to  him :  for  which  reason  the  liberal 
man  takes  pleasure  in  giving  to  others.  The  third  principle 
is  the  motive:  for  instance  when  a  man  is  moved  by  one 
whom  he  loves,  to  do  good  to  someone;  for  whatever  we 
do  or  suffer  for  a  friend  is  pleasant,  because  love  is  the 
principal  cause  of  pleasure. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Spending  gives  pleasure  as  showing  forth 
one's  good.  But  in  so  far  as  it  empties  us  of  our  own  good 
it  may  be  a  cause  of  sadness;  for  instance  when  it  is  ex- 
cessive. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Prodigality  is  an  excessive  spending,  which 
is  unnatural:  wherefore  prodigality  is  said  to  be  contrary 
to  nature. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  To  overcome,  to  contradict  and  to  punish, 
give  pleasure,  not  as  tending  to  another's  ill,  but  as  pertain- 
ing to  one's  own  good,  which  man  loves  more  than  he  hates 
another's  ill.  For  it  is  naturally  pleasant  to  overcome, 
inasmuch  as  it  makes  a  man  to  appreciate  his  own  superi- 
ority. Wherefore  all  those  games  in  which  there  is  a 
striving  for  the  mastery,  and  a  possibility  of  winning  it, 
afford  the  greatest  pleasure:  and  speaking  generally  all 
contests,  in  so  far  as  they  admit  hope  of  victory. — ^To 
contradict  and  to  scold  can  give  pleasure  in  two  ways. 
First,  as  making  man  imagine  himself  to  be  wise  and  ex- 
cellent; since  it  belongs  to  wise  men  and  elders  to  reprove 
and  to  scold.  Secondly,  in  so  far  as  by  scolding  and  reprov- 
ing, one  does  good  to  another:  for  this  gives  one  pleasure, 
as  stated  above. — It  is  pleasant  to  an  angry  man  to  punish, 
in  so  far  as  he  thinks  himself  to  be  removing  an  apparent 


OF  THE  CAUSE  OF  PLEASURE  383 

slight,  which  seems  to  be  due  to  a  previous  hurt :  for  when  a 
man  is  hurt  by  another,  he  seems  to  be  slighted  thereby; 
and  therefore  he  wishes  to  be  quit  of  this  slight  by  paying 
back  the  hurt. — And  thus  it  is  clear  that  doing  good  to 
another  may  be  of  itself  pleasant:  whereas  doing  evil  to 
another  is  not  pleasant,  except  in  so  far  as  it  seems  to  affect 
one's  own  good. 

Seventh  Article, 
whether  likeness  is  a  cause  of  pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 
'  Objection  i.  It  seems  that  likeness  is  not  a  cause  of 
pleasure.  Because  ruling  and  presiding  seem  to  imply 
a  certain  unlikeness.  But  it  is  natural  to  take  pleasure  in 
ruling  and  presiding,  as  stated  in  Rhet.  i.  Therefore  unlike- 
ness, rather  than  likeness,  is  a  cause  of  pleasure. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  nothing  is  more  unlike  pleasure  than 
sorrow.  But  those  who  are  burdened  by  sorrow  are  most 
inclined  to  seek  pleasures,  as  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic. 
vii.).  Therefore  unlikeness,  rather  than  likeness,  is  a  cause 
of  pleasure. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  those  who  are  satiated  with  certain 
delights,  derive  not  pleasure  but  disgust  from  them ;  as  when 
one  is  satiated  with  food.  Therefore  likeness  is  not  a  cause 
of  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  Likeness  is  a  cause  of  love,  as  above 
stated  (Q.  XXVIL,  A.  3) :  and  love  is  the  cause  of  pleasure. 
Therefore  likeness  is  a  cause  of  pleasure. 

/  answer  that,  Likeness  is  a  kind  of  unity ;  hence  that  which 
is  like  us,  as  being  one  with  us,  causes  pleasure;  just  as  it 
causes  love,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXVIL,  A.  3).  And  if  that 
which  is  like  us  does  not  hurt  our  own  good,  but  increase 
it,  it  is  pleasurable  simply;  for  instance  one  man  in  respect 
if  another,  one  youth  in  relation  to  another. — But  if  it  be 
hurtful  to  our  own  good,  thus  accidentally  it  causes  disgust 
or  sadness,  not  as  being  like  and  one  with  us,  but  as  hurtful 
to  that  which  is  yet  more  one  with  us. 

Now  it  happens  in  two  ways  that  something  like  is  hurtful 


384  QUESTION  XXXII 

to  our  own  good.  First;  by  destroying  the  measure  of  our 
own  good,  by  a  kind  of  excess ;  because  good,  chiefly  bodily 
good,  as  health,  is  conditioned  by  a  certain  measure:  where- 
fore superfluous  food  or  any  bodily  pleasure,  causes  dis- 
gust.— Secondly,  by  being  directly  contrary  to  one's  own 
good :  thus  a  potter  dislikes  other  potters,  not  because  they 
are  potters,  but  because  they  deprive  him  of  his  own  excel- 
lence or  profits,  which  he  seeks  as  his  own  good. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Since  ruler  and  subject  are  in  communion 
with  one  another,  there  is  a  certain  likeness  between  them: 
but  this  likeness  is  conditioned  by  a  certain  superiority, 
since  ruling  and  presiding  pertain  to  the  excellence  of  a 
man's  own  good:  because  they  belong  to  men  who  are  wise 
and  better  than  others;  the  result  being  that  they  give 
man  an  idea  of  his  own  excellence. — -Another  reason  is  that 
by  ruling  and  presiding,  a  man  does  good  to  others,  which  is 
pleasant. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  That  which  gives  pleasure  to  the  sorrowful 
man,  though  it  be  unlike  sorrow,  bears  some  likeness  to  the 
man  that  is  sorrowful:  because  sorrows  are  contrary  to  his 
own  good.  Wherefore  the  sorrowful  man  seeks  pleasure 
as  making  for  his  own  good,  in  so  far  as  it  is  a  remedy  for 
its  contrary.  And  this  is  why  bodily  pleasures,  which  are 
contrary  to  certain  sorrows,  are  more  sought  than  intel- 
lectual pleasures,  which  have  no  contrary  sorrow,  as  we  shall 
state  later  on  (Q.  XXXV.,  A.  5).  And.  this  explains  why 
all  animals  naturally  desire  pleasure:  because  animals  ever 
work  through  sense  and  movement.  For  this  reason  also 
young  people  are  most  inclined  to  seek  pleasures ;  on  account 
of  the  many  changes  to  which  they  are  subject,  while  yet 
growing.  Moreover  this  is  why  the  melancholic  has  a  strong 
desire  for  pleasures,  in  order  to  drive  away  sorrow :  because 
his  body  is  corroded  by  a  base  humour,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  vii. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Bodily  goods  are  conditioned  by  a  certain 
fixed  measure:  wherefore  surfeit  of  such  things  destroys 
the  proper  good,  and  consequently  gives  rise  to  disgust  and 
sorrow,  through  being  contrary  to  the  proper  good  of  man. 


OF  THE  CAUSE  OF  PLEASURE  385 

Eighth  Article, 
whether  wonder  is  a  cause  of  pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — • 

Objection  i .  It  seems  that  wonder  is  not  a  cause  of  pleasure. 
Because  wonder  is  the  act  of  one  who  is  ignorant  of  the 
nature  of  something,  as  Damascene  says.  But  knowledge, 
rather  than  ignorance,  is  a  cause  of  pleasure.  Therefore 
wonder  is  not  a  cause  of  pleasure. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  wonder  is  the  beginning  of  wisdom,  being, 
as  it  were,  the  road  to  the  search  of  truth,  as  stated  in  the 
beginning  of  Metaph.  (ii.).  But  it  is  more  pleasant  to  think 
of  what  we  know,  than  to  seek  for  what  we  know  not,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  x.)  :  since  in  the  latter  case  we 
encounter  difficulties  and  hindrances,  in  the  former  not; 
while  pleasure  arises  from  an  operation  which  is  unhindered, 
as  stated  in  Ethic,  vii.  Therefore  wonder  hinders  rather 
than  causes  pleasure. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  everyone  takes  pleasure  in  what  he  is 
accustomed  to :  wherefore  the  actions  of  habits  acquired  by 
custom,  are  pleasant.  But  we  wonder  at  what  is  unwonted, 
as  Augustine  says  [Tract,  xxiv.  in  Joan.).  Therefore 
wonder  is  contrary  to  the  cause  of  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  i.)  that  wonder 
is  the  cause  of  pleasure. 

/  answer  that,  It  is  pleasant  to  get  what  one  desires,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  XXIII. ,  A.  4):  and  therefore  the  greater 
the  desire  for  the  thing  loved,  the  greater  the  pleasure  when 
it  is  attained:  indeed  the  very  increase  of  desire  brings 
with  it  an  increase  of  pleasure,  according  as  it  gives  rise  to 
the  hope  of  obtaining  that  which  is  loved,  since  it  was 
stated  above  (A.  3  ad  3)  that  desire  resulting  from  liope 
is  a  cause  of  pleasure. — Now  wonder  is  a  kind  of  desire  for 
knowledge  ;  a  desire  which  comes  to  man  when  he  sees  an 
effect  of  which  the  cause  either  is  unknown  to  him,  or  sur- 
passes his  knowledge  or  faculty  of  understanding.  Conse- 
quently wonder  is  a  cause  of  pleasure,  in  so  far  as  it  includes 

II.  I  2.=, 


386  QUESTION  XXXII 

a  hope  of  getting  the  knowledge  which  one  desires  to  have. 
For  this  reason  whatever  is  wonderful  is  pleasing,  for  instance 
things  that  are  scarce.  Also,  representations  of  things, 
even  of  those  which  are  not  pleasant  in  themselves,  give 
rise  to  pleasure;  for  the  soul  rejoices  in  comparing  one  thing 
with  another,  because  comparison  of  one  thing  with  another 
is  the  proper  and  connatural  act  of  the  reason,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  {Poet.  iv.).  This  again  is  why  it  is  more 
delightful  to  he  delivered  from  great  danger,  because  it  is  some- 
thing  wonderful,  as  stated  in  Rhet.  i. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Wonder  gives  pleasure,  not  because  it 
implies  ignorance,  but  in  so  far  as  it  includes  the  desire  of 
learning  the  cause,  and  in  so  far  as  the  wonderer  learns 
something  new,  i.e.,  thdit  the  cause  is  other  than  he  had 
thought  it  to  be.* 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Pleasure  includes  two  things;  rest  in  the 
good,  and  perception  of  this  rest.  As  to  the  former  there- 
fore, since  it  is  more  perfect  to  contemplate  the  known  truth, 
than  to  seek  for  the  unknown,  the  contemplation  of  what  we 
know,  is  in  itself  more  pleasing  than  the  research  of  what  we 
do  not  know.  Nevertheless,  as  to  the  second,  it  happens 
that  research  is  sometimes  more  pleasing  accidentally,  in 
so  far  as  it  proceeds  from  a  greater  desire :  for  greater  desire 
is  awakened  when  we  are  conscious  of  our  ignorance.  This 
is  why  man  takes  the  greatest  pleasure  in  finding  or  learning 
things  for  the  first  time. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  It  is  pleasant  to  do  what  we  are  wont  to  do, 
inasmuch  as  this  is  connatural  to  us,  as  it  were.  And  yet 
things  that  are  of  rare  occurrence  can  be  pleasant,  either  as 
regards  knowledge,  from  the  fact  that  we  desire  to  know 
something  about  them,  in  so  far  as  they  are  wonderful;  or 
as  regards  action,  from  the  fact  that  the  mind  is  more  in- 
clined hy  desire  to  act  intensely  in  things  that  are  new,  as  stated 
in  Ethic,  x.,  since  more  perfect  operation  causes  more  perfect 
pleasure. 

*  According  to  another  reading: — that  he  is  other  than  he  thought 
himself  to  be. 


QUESTION  XXXIIL 

OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  PLEASURE. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  effects  of  pleasure;  and  under 
this  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether 
expansion  is  an  effect  of  pleasure  ?  (2)  Whether  pleasure 
causes  thirst  or  desire  for  itself  ?  (3)  Whether  pleasure 
hinders  the  use  of  reason  ?  (4)  Whether  pleasure  perfects 
operation  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  expansion  is  an  effect  of  pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  expansion  is  not  an  effect  of 
pleasure.  For  expansion  seems  to  pertain  more  to  love, 
according  to  the  Apostle  (2  Cor.  vi.  11) :  Our  heart  is  enlarged. 
Wherefore  it  is  written  (Ps.  cxviii.  6)  concerning  the  precept 
of  charity:  Thy  commandment  is  exceeding  broad.  But 
pleasure  is  a  distinct  passion  from  love.  Therefore  expan- 
sion is  not  an  effect  of  pleasure. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  when  a  thing  expands  it  is  enabled  to 
receive  more.  But  receiving  pertains  to  desire,  which  is  for 
something  not  yet  possessed.  Therefore  expansion  seems 
to  belong  to  desire  rather  than  to  pleasure. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  contraction  is  contrary  to  expansion. 
But  contraction  seems  to  belong  to  pleasure,  for  the  hand 
closes  on  that  which  we  wish  to  grasp  firmly :  and  such  is 
the  affection  of  appetite  in  regard  to  that  which  pleases 
it.     Therefore  expansion  does  not  pertain  to  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,   In  order  to  express  joy,   it   is  written 

3«7 


388  QUESTION  XXXTII 

(Isa.  Ix.  5) :  Thou  shall  see  and  abound,  thy  heart  shall  wonder 
and  he  enlarged.  Moreover  pleasure  is  called  by  the  name  of 
laetitia,  ^?>hemg  derived  from  ^^/^z^a/^'o  (expansion),  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XXXI.,  A.  3,  ad  3). 

/  answer  that,  Breadth  {latitudo)  is  a  dimension  of  bodily 
magnitude:  hence  it  is  not  applied  to  the  emotions  of  the 
soul,  save  metaphorically.  Now  expansion  denotes  a  kind 
of  movement  towards  breadth ;  and  it  belongs  to  pleasure 
in  respect  of  the  two  things  requisite  for  pleasure.  One  of 
these  is  on  the  part  of  the  apprehensive  power,  which  is 
cognizant  of  the  conjunction  with  some  suitable  good.  As 
a  result  of  this  apprehension,  man  perceives  that  he  has 
attained  a  certain  perfection,  which  is  a  magnitude  of  the 
spiritual  order:  and  in  this  respect  man's  mind  is  said  to 
be  magnified  or  expanded  by  pleasure.— The  other  requisite 
for  pleasure  is  on  the  part  of  the  appetitive  power,  which 
acquiesces  in  the  pleasurable  object,  and  rests  therein, 
offering,  as  it  were,  to  enfold  it  within  itself.  And  thus 
man's  affection  is  expanded  by  pleasure,  as  though  it  sur- 
rendered itself  to  hold  within  itself  the  object  of  its  pleasure. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  In  metaphorical  expressions  nothing 
hinders  one  and  the  same  thing  from  being  compared  to 
different  things  according  to  different  likenesses.  And  in 
this  way  expansion  pertains  to  love  by  reason  of  a  certain 
spreading  out,  in  so  far  as  the  affection  of  the  lover  spreads 
out  to  others,  so  as  to  care,  not  only  for  his  own  interests, 
but  also  for  what  concerns  others.  On  the  other  hand 
expansion  pertains  to  pleasure,  in  so  far  as  a  thing  becomes 
more  ample  in  itself  so  as  to  become  more  capacious. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Desire  includes  a  certain  expansion  arising 
from  the  imagination  of  the  thing  desired ;  but  this  expansion 
increases  at  the  presence  of  the  pleasurable  object:  because 
the  mind  surrenders  itself  more  to  that  object  when  it  is 
already  taking  pleasure  in  it,  than  when  it  desires  it  before 
possessing  it ;  since  pleasure  is  the  end  of  desire. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  He  that  takes  pleasure  in  a  thing  holds  it 
fast,  by  clinging  to  it  with  all  his  might :  but  he  opens  his 
heart  to  it  that  he  may  enjoy  it  perfectly. 


OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  PLEASURE  389 


Second  Article, 
whether  pleasure  causes  thirst  or  desire  for 

ITSELF  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  pleasure  does  not  cause  desire 
for  itself.  Because  all  movement  ceases  when  repose  is 
reached.  But  pleasure  is,  as  it  were,  a  certain  repose  of 
the  movement  of  desire,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXIII.,  A.  4; 
Q.  XXV.,  A.  2).  Therefore  the  movement  of  desire  ceases 
when  pleasure  is  reached.  Therefore  pleasure  does  not 
cause  desire. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  a  thing  does  not  cause  its  contrary. 
But  pleasure  is,  in  a  way,  contrary  to  desire,  on  the  part  of 
the  object:  since  desire  regards  a  good  which  is  not  yet 
possessed,  whereas  pleasure  regards  the  good  that  is  pos- 
sessed.    Therefore  pleasure  does  not  cause  desire  for  itself. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  distaste  is  incompatible  with  desire. 
But  pleasure  often  causes  distaste.  Therefore  it  does  not 
cause  desire. 

On  the  contrary,  Our  Lord  said  (John  iv.  13) :  Whosoever 
drinketh  of  this  water,  shall  thirst  again  :  where,  according 
to  Augustine  {Tract,  xv.  in  Joan.),  water  denotes  pleasures 
of  the  body. 

I  answer  that,  Pleasure  can  be  considered  in  two  ways; 
first,  as  existing  in  reality;  secondly,  as  existing  in  the 
memory. — Again  thirst,  or  desire,  can  be  taken  in  two  ways; 
first,  properly,  as  denoting  a  craving  for  something  not 
possessed;  secondly,  in  genera],  as  excluding  distaste. 

Considered  as  existing  in  reality,  pleasure  does  not  cause 
thirst  or  desire  for  itself,  properly  speaking;  provided  we 
take  thirst  or  desire  as  denoting  a  craving  for  something  not 
possessed:  because  pleasure  is  an  emotion  of  the  appetite 
in  respect  of  something  actually  present. — But  it  may 
happen  that  what  is  actually  present  is  not  perfectly  pos- 
sessed: and  this  may  be  on  the  part  of  the  thing  possessed, 
or  on  the  .part  of  the  possessor.     On  the  part  of  the  thing 


390  QUESTION  XXXIII 

possessed,  this  happens  through  the  thing  possessed  not 
being  a  simultaneous  whole;  wherefore  one  obtains  posses- 
sion of  it  successively,  and  while  taking  pleasure  in  what 
one  has,  one  desires  to  possess  the  remainder :  thus  if  a  man 
is  pleased  with  the  first  part  of  a  verse,  he  desires  to  hear 
the  second  part,  as  Augustine  says  (Conf.  iv.).  In  this 
way  nearly  all  bodily  pleasures  cause  thirst  for  themselves, 
until  they  are  fully  realized,  because  pleasures  of  this  kind 
arise  from  some  movement:  as  is  evident  in  pleasures  of 
the  table. — On  the  part  of  the  possessor,  this  happens  when 
a  man  possesses  a  thing  which  is  perfect  in  itself,  yet  does 
not  possess  it  perfectly,  but  obtains  possession  of  it  little 
by  little.  Thus  in  this  life,  a  faint  perception  of  Divine 
knowledge  affords  us  delight,  and  delight  sets  up  a  thirst 
or  desire  for  perfect  knowledge;  in  which  sense  we  may 
understand  the  words  of  Ecclus.  xxiv.  29:  They  that  drink 
me  shall  yet  thirst. 

On  the  other  hand  if  by  thirst  or  desire  we  understand 
the  mere  intensity  of  the  emotion,  that  excludes  distaste, 
thus  more  than  all  others  spiritual  pleasures  cause  thirst  or 
desire  for  themselves.  Because  bodily  pleasures  become 
distasteful  by  reason  of  their  causing  an  excess  in  the  natural 
mode  of  being,  when  they  are  increased  or  even  when  they 
are  protracted;  as  is  evident  in  the  case  of  pleasures  of  the 
table.  This  is  why,  when  a  man  arrives  at  the  point  of 
perfection  in  bodily  pleasures,  he  wearies  of  them,  and  some- 
times desires  another  kind. — Spiritual  pleasures,  on  the 
contrary,  do  not  exceed  the  natural  mode  of  being,  but 
perfect  nature.  Hence  when  their  point  of  perfection  is 
reached,  then  do  they  afford  the  greatest  delight:  except, 
perchance,  accidentally,  in  so  far  as  the  work  of  contempla- 
tion is  accompanied  by  some  operation  of  the  bodily  powers, 
which  tire  from  protracted  activity.  And  in  this  sense  also 
we  may  understand  those  words  of  Ecclus.  xxiv.  29:  They 
that  drink  me  shall  yet  thirst :  for,  even  of  the  angels,  who 
know  God  perfectly,  and  delight  in  Him,  it  is  written  (i  Pet. 
i.  12)  that  they  desire  to  look  at  Him. 

Lastly,  if  we  consider  pleasure,  not  as  existing  in  reality. 


OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  PLEASURE  391 

but  as  existing  in  the  memory,  thus  it  has  of  itself  a  natural 
tendency  to  cause  thirst  and  desire  for  itself :  when,  to  wit, 
man  returns  to  that  disposition,  in  which  he  was  when  he 
experienced  the  pleasure  that  is  past.  But  if  he  be  changed 
from  that  disposition,  the  memory  of  that  pleasure  does  not 
give  him  pleasure,  but  distaste:  for  instance,  the  memory 
of  food  in  respect  of  a  man  who  has  ate  to  repletion. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  When  pleasure  is  perfect,  then  it  includes 
complete  rest ;  and  the  movement  of  desire,  tending  to  what 
was  not  possessed,  ceases.  But  when  it  is  imperfect,  then 
the  desire,  tending  to  what  was  not  possessed,  does  not 
cease  altogether. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  That  which  is  possessed  imperfectly,  is  pos- 
sessed in  one  respect,  and  in  another  respect  is  not  pos- 
sessed. Consequently  it  may  be  the  object  of  desire  and 
pleasure  at  the  same  time. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Pleasures  cause  distaste  in  one  way,  desire 
in  another,  as  stated  above. 

Third  Article, 
whether  pleasure  hinders  the  use  of  reason  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  pleasure  does  not  hinder  the 
use  of  reason.  Because  repose  facilitates  very  much  the  due 
use  of  reason:  wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  (Phys.  vii.) 
that  while  we  sit  and  rest  the  soul  is  inclined  to  knowledge  and 
prudence  ;  and  it  is  written  (Wisd.  viii.  16) :  When  I  go  into 
my  house,  I  shall  repose  myself  with  her,  i.e.,  wisdom.  But 
pleasure  is  a  kind  of  repose.  Therefore  it  helps  rather  than 
hinders  the  use  of  reason. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  things  which  are  not  in  the  same  subject 
though  they  be  contraries,  do  not  hinder  one  another. 
But  pleasure  is  in  the  appetitive  faculty,  while  the  use  of 
reason  is  in  the  apprehensive  power.  Therefore  pleasure 
does  not  hinder  the  use  of  reason. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  that  which  is  hindered  by  another, 
seems  to  be  moved,  as  it  were,  thereby.     But  the  use  of  an 


392     .  QUESTION  XXXIII 

apprehensive  power  moves  pleasure  rather  than  is  moved 
by  it :  because  it  is  the  cause  of  pleasure.  Therefore  pleasure 
does  not  hinder  the  use  of  reason. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  vi.),  that 
pleasure  destroys  the  estimate  of  prudence. 

I  answer  that,  As  is  stated  in  Ethic,  x.,  appropriate  pleasures 
increase  activity  .  .  .  whereas  pleasures  arising  from  other 
sources  are  impediments  to  activity.  Accordingly  there  is 
a  certain  pleasure  that  is  taken  in  the  very  act  of  reason, 
as  when  one  takes  pleasure  in  contemplating  or  in  reasoning : 
and  such  pleasure  does  not  hinder  the  act  of  reason,  but 
helps  it;  because  we  are  more  attentive  in  doing  that  which 
gives  us  pleasure,  and  attention  fosters  activity. 

On  the  other  hand  bodily  pleasures  hinder  the  use  of 
reason  in  three  ways.  First,  by  distracting  the  reason. 
Because,  as  we  have  just  observed,  we  attend  much  to  that 
which  pleases  us.  Now  when  the  attention  is  firmly  fixed 
on  one  thing,  it  is  either  weakened  in  respect  of  other  things, 
or  it  is  entirely  withdrawn  from  them;  and  thus  if  the 
bodily  pleasure  be  great,  either  it  entirely  hinders  the  use 
of  reason,  by  concentrating  the  mind's  attention  on  itself; 
or  else  it  hinders  it  considerably .— Secondly,  by  being  con- 
trary to  reason.  Because  some  pleasures,  especially  those 
that  are  in  excess,  are  contrarv  to  the  order  of  reason :  and 
in  this  sense  the  Philosopher  says  that  bodily  pleasures 
destroy  the  estimate  of  prudence,  but  not  the  speculative  estimate, 
to  which  they  are  not  opposed,  for  instance  that  the  three 
angles  of  a  triangle  are  together  equal  to  two  right  angles.  In 
the  first  sense,  however,  they  hinder  both  estimates. — • 
Thirdly,  by  fettering  the  reason :  in  so  far  as  bodily  pleasure 
is  followed  by  a  certain  alteration  in  the  body,  greater  even 
than  in  the  other  passions,  in  proportion  as  the  appetite 
is  more  vehemently  affected  towards  a  present  than  towards 
an  absent  thing.  Now  such  bodily  disturbances  hinder  the 
use  of  reason;  as  may  be  seen  in  the  case  of  drunkards, 
in  whom  the  use  of  reason  is  fettered  or  hindered. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Bodily  pleasure  implies  indeed  repose  of 
the  appetite  in  the  object  of  pleasure;  which  repose  is  some- 


OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  PLEASURE  393 

times  contrary  to  reason;  but  on  the  part  of  the  body  it 
always  imphes  alteration.  And  in  respect  of  both  points, 
it  hinders  the  use  of  reason. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  powers  of  appetite  and  of  apprehension 
are  indeed  distinct  parts,  but  belonging  to  the  one  soul. 
Consequently  when  the  soul  is  very  intent  on  the  action  of 
one  part,  it  is  hindered  from  attending  to  a  contrary  act 
of  the  other  part. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  use  of  reason  requires  the  due  use  of 
the  imagination  and  of  the  other  sensitive  powers,  which  are 
exercised  through  a  bodily  organ.  Consequently  alteration 
in  the  body  hinders  the  use  of  reason,  because  it  hinders 
the  acts  of  the  imagination  and  of  the  other  sensitive 
powers. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  pleasure  perfects  operation  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  :-- 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  pleasure  does  not  perfect 
operation.  For  every  human  operation  depends  on  the  use 
of  reason.  But  pleasure  hinders  the  use  of  reason,  as  stated 
above  (A.  3).  Therefore  pleasure  does  not  perfect,  but 
weakens  human  operation. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  nothing  perfects  itself  or  its  cause.  But 
pleasure  is  an  operation  (Ethic,  vii,,  x.),  i.e.,  either  in  its 
essence  or  in  its  cause.  Therefore  pleasure  does  not  perfect 
operation. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  if  pleasure  perfects  operation,  it  does  so 
either  as  end,  or  as  form,  or  as  agent.  But  not  as  end; 
because  operation  is  not  sought  for  the  sake  of  pleasure, 
but  rather  the  reverse,  as  stated  above  (Q.  IV.,  A.  2):  nor 
as  agent,  because  rather  is  it  the  operation  that  causes 
pleasure:  nor  again  as  form,  because,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  {Ethic,  x.),  pleasure  does  not  perfect  operation, 
as  a  hahit  does.  Therefore  pleasure  does  not  perfect 
operation. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (ihid.)  that  pleasure 
perfects  operation. 


394  QUESTION  XXXITT 

/  answer  that,  Pleasure  perfects  operation  in  two  ways. 
First,  as  an  end:  not  indeed  according  as  an  end  is  that  on 
account  of  which  a  thing  is  ;  but  according  as  every  good 
which  is  added  to  a  thing  and  completes  it,  can  be  called 
its  end.  And  in  this  sense  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  x.) 
that  pleasure  perfects  operation  .  .  .  as  some  end  added  to  it : 
that  is  to  say,  inasmuch  as  to  this  good,  which  is  operation, 
there  is  added  another  good,  which  is  pleasure,  denoting 
the  repose  of  the  appetite  in  a  good  that  is  presupposed. — 
Secondly,  as  agent;  for  the  Philosopher  says  (ibid.)  that 
pleasure  perfects  operation,  not  as  a  physician  makes  a  man 
healthy,  but  as  health  does  :  but  it  does  so  indirectly ;  inas- 
much as  the  agent,  through  taking  pleasure  in  his  action, 
is  more  eagerly  intent  on  it,  and  carries  it  out  with  greater 
care.  And  in  this  sense  it  is  said  in  Ethic,  x.  that  pleasures 
increase  their  appropriate  activities,  and  hinder  those  that  are 
not  appropriate. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  It  is  not  every  pleasure  that  hinders  the  act 
of  reason,  but  only  bodily  pleasure ;  for  this  arises,  not  from 
the  act  of  reason,  but  from  the  act  of  the  concupiscible 
faculty,  which  act  is  intensified  by  pleasure.  On  the  con- 
trary, pleasure  that  arises  from  the  act  of  reason,  strengthens 
the  use  of  reason. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  stated  in  Phys.  ii.,  two  things  may  be 
causes  of  one  another,  if  one  be  the  efficient,  the  other  the 
final  cause.  And  in  this  way,  operation  is  the  efficient  cause 
of  pleasure,  while  pleasure  perfects  operation  by  way  of  final 
cause,  as  stated  above. 

The  Reply  to  the  Third  Objection  is  evident  from  what 
has  been  said. 


QUESTION  XXXIV. 

OF  THE  GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  OF  PLEASURES 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  goodness  and  malice  of  pleasures : 
under  which  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether 
every  pleasure  is  evil  ?  (2)  If  not,  whether  every  pleasure  is 
good  ?  (3)  Whether  any  pleasure  is  the  greatest  good  ? 
(4)  Whether  pleasure  is  the  measure  or  rule  by  which  to  judge 
of  moral  good  and  evil  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  every  pleasure  is  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  every  pleasure  is  evil.  For 
that  which  destroys  prudence  and  hinders  the  use  of  reason, 
seems  to  be  evil  in  itself :  since  man's  good  is  to  be  in  accord 
with  reason,  as  Dionysius  says  {Div.  Nom.  iv.).  But  pleasure 
destroys  prudence  and  hinders  the  use  of  reason;  and  so 
much  the  more,  as  the  pleasure  is  greater:  wherefore  in 
sexual  -pleasures,  which  are  the  greatest  of  all,  it  is  impossible 
to  understand  anything,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  vii.  Moreover, 
Jerome  says  in  his  commentary  on  Matthew  (Origen, — 
Horn.  vi.  in  Num.)  that  at  the  time  of  conjugal  intercourse, 
the  presence  of  the  Holy  Ghost  is  not  vouchsafed,  even  if  it  be 
a  prophet  that  fulfils  the  conjugal  duty.  Therefore  pleasure  is 
evil  in  itself;  and  consequently  every  pleasure  is  evil. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  that  which  the  virtuous  man  shuns,  and 
the  ungodly  man  seeks,  seems  to  be  evil  in  itself,  and  should 
be  avoided;  because,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  x.,  the  virtuous  man 

395 


396  QUESTION  XXXIV 

is  a  kind  of  meastire  and  rule  of  human  actions  ;  and  the 
Apostle  says  (i  Cor.  ii.  15):  The  spiritual  man  judgeth  all 
things.  But  children  and  dumb  animals,  in  whom  there  is 
no  virtue,  seek  pleasure:  whereas  the  man  who  is  master 
of  himself  does  not.  Therefore  pleasures  are  evil  in  them- 
selves and  should  be  avoided. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  virtue  and  art  are  concerned  about  the 
difficult  and  the  good  {Ethic,  ii.).  But  no  art  is  ordained  to 
pleasure.     Therefore  pleasure  is  not  something  good. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ps.  xxxvi.  4):  Delight  in  the 
Lord.  Since,  therefore.  Divine  authority  leads  to  no  evil, 
it  seems  that  not  every  pleasure  is  evil. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  in  Ethic,  x.,  some  have  maintained 
that  all  pleasure  is  evil.  The  reason  seems  to  have  been 
that  they  took  account  only  of  sensible  and  bodily  pleasures 
which  are  more  manifest;  since,  also  in  other  respects,  the 
ancient  philosophers  did  not  discriminate  between  the  in- 
telhgible  and  the  sensible,  or  between  intellect  and  sense 
{cf.  Be  Anima  iii.).  And  they  held  that  all  bodily  pleasures 
should  be  reckoned  as  bad,  and  thus  that  man,  being  prone 
to  immoderate  pleasures,  arrives  at  the  mean  of  virtue  by 
abstaining  from  pleasure. — But  they  were  wrong  in  holding 
this  opinion.  Because,  since  none  can  live  without  some 
sensible  and  bodily  pleasure,  if  they  who  teach  that  all 
pleasures  are  evil,  are  found  in  the  act  of  taking  pleasure; 
men  will  be  more  inclined  to  pleasure  by  following  the 
example  of  their  works  instead  of  listening  to  the  doctrine 
of  their  words :  since,  in  human  actions  and  passions,  wherein 
experience  is  of  great  weight,  example  moves  more  than  words. 

We  must  therefore  say  that  some  pleasures  are  good, 
and  that  some  are  evil.  For  pleasure  is  a  repose  of  the 
appetitive  power  in  some  loved  good,  and  resulting  from 
some  operation ;  wherefore  we  may  assign  a  twofold  reason 
for  this  assertion.  The  first  is  in  respect  of  the  good  in 
which  a  man  reposes  with  pleasure.  For  good  and  evil 
in  the  moral  order  depend  on  agreement  or  disagree- 
ment with  reason,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XVIII. ,  A.  5):  just 
as  in  the  order  of  nature,  a  thing  is  said  to  be  natural,  if  it 


GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  OF  PLEASURES      397 

agrees  with  nature,  and  unnatural,  if  it  disagrees.  Accord- 
ingly, just  as  in  the  natural  order  there  is  a  certain  natural 
repose,  whereby  a  thing  rests  in  that  which  agrees  with  its 
nature,  for  instance,  when  a  heavy  body  rests  down  below ; 
and  again  an  unnatural  repose,  whereby  a  thing  rests  in 
that  which  disagrees  with  its  nature,  as  when  a  heavy  body 
rests  up  aloft :  so,  in  the  moral  order,  there  is  a  good  pleasure, 
whereby  the  higher  or  lower  appetite  rests  in  that  which  is 
in  accord  with  reason;  and  an  evil  pleasure,  whereby  the 
appetite  rests  in  that  which  is  discordant  from  reason  and 
the* law  of  God. 

The  second  reason  can  be  found  by  considering  the  actions, 
some  of  which  are  good,  some  evil.  Now  pleasures  which 
are  conjoined  to  actions  are  more  akin  to  those  actions,  than 
desires,  which  precede  them  in  point  of  time.  Wherefore, 
since  the  desires  of  good  actions  are  good,  and  of  evil  actions, 
evil ;  much  more  are  the  pleasures  of  good  actions  good,  and 
those  of  evil  actions  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXVIIL,  A.  3),  it  is  not 
the  pleasures  which  result  from  an  act  of  reason,  that  hinder 
the  reason  or  destroy  prudence,  but  extraneous  pleasures, 
such  as  the  pleasures  of  the  body.  These  indeed  hinder  the 
use  of  reason,  as  stated  above  {ibid.),  either  by  contrariety 
of  the  appetite  that  rests  in  something  repugnant  to  reason, 
which  makes  the  pleasure  morally  bad;  or  by  fettering  the 
reason:  thus  in  conjugal  intercourse,  though  the  pleasure 
be  in  accord  with  reason,  yet  it  hinders  the  use  of  reason, 
on  account  of  the  accompanying  bodily  change.  But  in 
this  case  the  pleasure  is  not  morally  evil ;  as  neither  is  sleep, 
whereby  the  reason  is  fettered,  morally  evil,  if  it  be  taken 
according  to  reason :  for  reason  itself  demands  that  the  use 
of  reason  be  interrupted  at  times. — ^We  must  add,  however, 
that  although  this  fettering  of  the  reason,  in  conjugal  inter- 
course, has  no  moral  malice,  since  it  is  neither  a  mortal  nor 
a  venial  sin;  yet  it  proceeds  from  a  kind  of  moral  malice, 
namely,  from  the  sin  of  our  first  parent;  because,  as  stated 
in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XCVIIL,  A.  2)  the  case  was  different 
in  the  state  of  innocence. 


398  QUESTION  XXXIV 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  temperate  man  does  not  shun  all 
pleasures,  but  those  that  are  immoderate,  and  contrary  to 
reason.  The  fact  that  children  and  dumb  animals  seek 
pleasures,  does  not  prove  that  all  pleasures  are  evil :  because 
they  have  from  God  their  natural  appetite,  which  is  moved 
to  that  which  is  naturally  suitable  to  them. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Art  is  not  concerned  with  all  kinds  of  good, 
but  with  the  making  of  external  things,  as  we  shall  state 
further  on  (Q.  LVIL,  A.  3).  But  prudence  and  virtue  are 
more  concerned  with  actions  and  passions  than  art  is. 
Nevertheless  there  is  an  art  of  making  pleasure,  namely, 
the  art  of  cookery  and  the  art  of  making  unguents,  as  stated  in 
Ethic,  vii. 

Second  Article, 
whether  every  pleasure  is  good  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i .  It  seems  that  every  pleasure  is  good.  Because 
as  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  V.,  A.  6),  there  are  three  kinds 
of  good,  the  virtuous,  the  useful,  and  the  pleasant.  But 
everything  virtuous  is  good;  and  in  like  manner  everything 
useful  is  good.     Therefore  also  every  pleasure  is  good. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  that  which  is  not  sought  for  the  sake  of 
something  else,  is  good  in  itself,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  i.  But 
pleasure  is  not  sought  for  the  sake  of  something  else ;  for  it 
seems  absurd  to  ask  anyone  why  he  seeks  to  be  pleased. 
Therefore  pleasure  is  good  in  itself.  Now  that  which  is 
predicated  of  a  thing  considered  in  itself,  is  predicated  thereof 
universally.     Therefore  every  pleasure  is  good. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  that  which  is  desired  by  all,  seems  to  be 
good  of  itself :  because  good  is  what  all  things  seek,  as  stated 
in  Ethic,  i.  But  everyone  seeks  some  kind  of  pleasure, 
even  children  and  dumb  animals.  Therefore  pleasure  is 
good  in  itself :  and  consequently  all  pleasure  is  good. 

On  the  contrary.  It  is  written  (Prov.  ii.  14) :  Who  are  glad 
when  they  have  done  evil,  and  rejoice  in  most  wicked  things. 

I  answer  that.  While  some  of  the  Stoics  maintained  that  all 
pleasures  are  evil,  the  Epicureans  held  that  pleasure  is  good 


GOODNESS  x\ND  MALICE  OF  PLEASURES      399 

in  itself,  and  that  consequently  all  pleasures  are  good. 
They  seem  to  have  thus  erred  through  not  discriminating 
between  that  which  is  good  simply,  and  that  which  is  good 
in  respect  of  a  particular  individual.  That  which  is  good 
simply,  is  good  in  itself.  Now  that  which  is  not  good  in 
itself,  may  be  good  in  respect  of  some  individual  in  two 
ways.  In  one  way,  because  it  is  suitable  to  him  by  reason 
of  a  disposition  in  which  he  is  now,  which  disposition, 
however,  is  not  natural:  thus  it  is  sometimes  good  for  a 
leper  to  eat  things  that  are  poisonous,  which  are  not  suitable 
simply  to  the  human  temperament.  In  another  way, 
through  something  unsuitable  being  esteemed  suitable. 
And  since  pleasure  is  the  repose  of  the  appetite  in  some  good, 
if  the  appetite  reposes  in  that  which  is  good  simply,  the 
pleasure  will  be  pleasure  simply,  and  good  simply.  But  if  a 
man's  appetite  repose  in  that  which  is  good,  not  simply,  but 
in  respect  of  that  particular  man,  then  his  pleasure  will  not 
be  pleasure  simply,  but  a  pleasure  to  him ;  neither  will  it  be 
good  simply,  but  in  a  certain  respect,  or  an  apparent  good. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  virtuous  and  the  useful  depend  on 
accordance  with  reason,  and  consequently  nothing  is  virtuous 
or  useful,  without  being  good.  But  the  pleasant  depends 
on  agreement  with  the  appetite,  which  tends  sometimes  to 
that  which  is  discordant  from  reason.  Consequently  not 
every  object  of  pleasure  is  good  in  the  moral  order  which 
depends  on  the  order  of  reason. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  reason  why  pleasure  is  not  sought  for 
the  sake  of  something  else  is  because  it  is  repose  in  the  end. 
Now  the  end  may  be  either  good  or  evil :  although  nothing 
can  be  an  end  except  in  so  far  as  it  is  good  in  respect  of  such 
and  such  a  man:  and  so  too  with  regard  to  pleasure. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  All  things  seek  pleasure  in  the  same  way  as 
they  seek  good:  since  pleasure  is  the  repose  of  the  appetite 
in  good.  But,  just  as  it  happens  that  not  every  good  which 
is  desired,  is  of  itself  and  verily  good;  so  not  every  pleasure 
is  of  itself  and  verily  good. 


400  QUESTION  XXXTV 

Third  Article, 
whether  any  pleasure  is  the  greatest  good  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  no  pleasure  is  the  greatest  good. 
Because  nothing  generated  is  the  greatest  good:  since 
generation  cannot  be  the  last  end.  But  pleasure  is  a  con- 
sequence of  generation:  for  the  fact  that  a  thing  takes 
pleasure  is  due  to  its  being  established  in  its  own  nature, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXI.,  A.  i).  Therefore  no  pleasure 
is  the  greatest  good. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  that  which  is  the  greatest  good  cannot 
be  made  better  by  addition.  But  pleasure  is  made  better 
by  addition;  since  pleasure  together  with  virtue  is  better 
than  pleasure  without  virtue.  Therefore  pleasure  is  not  the 
greatest  good. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  that  which  is  the  greatest  good  is  uni- 
versally good,  as  being  good  of  itself:  since  that  which  is 
such  of  itself  is  prior  to  and  greater  than  that  which  is  such 
accidentally.  But  pleasure  is  not  universally  good,  as 
stated  above  (A.  2).  Therefore  pleasure  is  not  the  greatest 
good. 

On  the  contrary,  Happiness  is  the  greatest  good :  since  it  is 
the  end  of  man's  life.  But  Happiness  is  not  without  pleasure : 
for  it  is  written  (Ps.  xv.  11) :  Thou  shalt  fill  me  with  joy  with 
Thy  countenance  ;  at  Thy  right  hand  are  delights  even  to  the 
end. 

I  answer  that,  Plato  held  neither  with  the  Stoics,  who 
asserted  that  all  pleasures  are  evil,  nor  with  the  Epicureans, 
who  maintained  that  all  pleasures  are  good;  but  he  said 
that  some  are  good,  and  some  evil;  yet,  so  that  no  pleasure 
be  the  sovereign  or  greatest  good.  But,  judging  from  his 
arguments,  he  fails  in  two  points.  First,  because,  from 
observing  that  sensible  and  bodily  pleasure  consist  in  a 
certain  movement  and  becoming,  as  is  evident  in  satiety 
from  eating  and  the  like ;  he  concluded  that  all  pleasure  arises 
from  some  becoming  and  movement:  and  from  this,  since 


GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  OF  PLEASURES      401 

becoming  and  movement  are  the  acts  of  something  imperfect, 
it  would  follow  that  pleasure  is  not  of  the  nature  of  ultimate 
perfection. — ^But  this  is  seen  to  be  evidently  false  as  regards 
intellectual  pleasures:  because  one  takes  pleasure,  not  only 
in  the  becoming  of  knowledge,  for  instance,  when  one  learns 
or  wonders,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXIL,  A.  8  ad  2);  but 
also  in  the  act  of  contemplation,  by  making  use  of  knowledge 
already  acquired. 

Secondly,  because  by  greatest  good  he  understood  that 
which  is  the  supreme  good  simply,  i.e.,  the  good  as  existing 
apart  from,  and  unparticipated  by,  all  else,  in  which  sense 
God  is  the  Supreme  Good:  whereas  we  are  speaking  of  the 
greatest  good  in  human  things.  Now  the  greatest  good  of 
everything  is  its  last  end.  And  the  end,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  L,  A.  8;  Q.  IL,A.  7)  is  twofold;  namely,  the  thing  itself, 
and  the  use  of  that  thing;  thus  the  miser's  end  is  either 
money,  or  the  possession  of  money.  Accordingly,  man's 
last  end  may  be  said  to  be  either  God  Who  is  the  Supreme 
Good  simply;  or  the  enjoyment  of  God,  which  denotes  a 
certain  pleasure  in  the  last  end.  And  in  this  sense  a  certain 
pleasure  of  man  may  be  said  to  be  the  greatest  among 
human  goods. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Not  every  pleasure  arises  from  a  becoming; 
for  some  pleasures  result  from  perfect  operations,  as 
stated  above.  iVccordingly  nothing  prevents  some  pleasure 
being  the  greatest  good,  although  every  pleasure  is  not 
such. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  This  argument  is  true  of  the  greatest  good 
simply,  by  participation  of  which  all  things  are  good; 
wherefore  no  addition  can  make  it  better :  whereas  in  regard 
to  other  goods,  it  is  universally  true  that  any  good  becomes 
better  by  the  addition  of  another  good. — Moreover  it  might 
be  said  that  pleasure  is  not  something  extraneous  to  the 
operation  of  virtue,  but  that  it  accompanies  it,  as  stated 
in  Ethic,  i. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  That  pleasure  is  the  greatest  good  is  due 
not  to  the  mere  fact  that  it  is  pleasure,  but  to  the  fact  that 
it  is  perfect  repose  in  the  perfect  good.     Hence  it  does  not 

II.  I  26 


402  QUESTION  XXXIV 

follow  that  every  pleasure  is  supremely  good,  or  even  good 
at  all.  Thus  a  certain  science  is  supremely  good,  but  not 
ever^T-  science  is. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  pleasure  is  the  measure  or  rule  by  which 
to  judge  of  moral  good  or  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  pleasure  is  not  the  measure  or 
rule  of  moral  good  and  evil.  Because  that  which  is  first  in 
a  genus  is  the  measure  of  all  the  rest  (Metaph.  x.).  But 
pleasure  is  not  the  first  thing  in  the  moral  genus,  for  it  is 
preceded  by  love  and  desire.  Therefore  it  is  not  the  rule 
of  goodness  and  malice  in  moral  matters. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  a  measure  or  rule  should  be  uniform: 
hence  that  movement  which  is  the  most  uniform,  is  the 
measure  and  rule  of  all  movements  (Metaph.  x.).  But 
pleasures  are  various  and  multiform :  since  some  of  them  are 
good,  and  some  evil.  Therefore  pleasure  is  not  the  measure 
and  rule  of  morals. 

Obj.  3.  Further^  judgment  of  the  effect  from  its  cause  is 
more  certain  than  judgment  of  cause  from  effect.  Now 
goodness  or  malice  of  operation  is  the  cause  of  goodness 
or  malice  of  pleasure :  because  those  pleasures  are  good  which 
result  from  good  operations,  and  those  are  evil  which  arise  from 
evil  operations,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  x.  Therefore  pleasures 
are  not  the  rule  and  measure  of  moral  goodness  and  malice. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine,  commenting  on  Ps.  vii.  10, 
The  searcher  of  hearts  and  reins  is  God,  says :  The  end  of  care 
and  thought  is  the  pleasure  which  each  one  aims  at  achieving. 
And  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vii.)  that  pleasure  is  the 
architect,  i.e.,  the  principal,  end,'^  in  regard  to  which,  we  say 
absolutely  that  this  is  evil,  and  that,  good. 

I  answer  that.  Moral  goodness  or  malice  depends  chiefly 
on  the  will,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XX.,  A.  i) ;  and  it  is  chiefly 

*  St.  Thomas  took  finis  as  being  the  nominative,  whereas  it  is 
the  genitive — tov  tcXovs  ;  hence  the  Greek  should  be  rendered  :  Pleasure 
IS  the  architect  of  the  end. 


GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  OF  PLEASURES     403 

from  the  end  that  we  discern  whether  the  will  is  good  or  evil. 
Now  the  end  is  taken  to  be  that  in  which  the  will  reposes: 
and  the  repose  of  the  will  and  of  every  appetite  in  the  good 
is  pleasure.  And  therefore  man  is  reckoned  to  be  good  or 
bad  chiefly  according  to  the  pleasure  of  the  human  will; 
since  that  man  is  good  and  virtuous,  who  takes  pleasure  in 
the  works  of  virtue ;  and  that  man  evil,  who  takes  pleasure 
in  evil  works. 

On  the  other  hand,  pleasures  of  the  sensitive  appetite  are 
not  the  rule  of  moral  goodness  and  malice:  since  good  is 
universally  pleasurable  to  the  sensitive  appetite  both  of  good 
and  of  evil  men.  But  the  will  of  the  good  man  takes  pleasure 
in  them  in  accordance  with  reason,  to  which  the  will  of  the 
evil  man  gives  no  heed. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Love  and  desire  precede  pleasure  in  the 
order  of  generation.  But  pleasure  precedes  them  in  the 
order  of  the  end,  which  stands  as  a  principle  in  the  matter 
of  morals:  and  it  is  by  the  principle,  which  is  the 
rule  and  measure  of  such  matters,  that  we  form  our 
judgment. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  All  pleasures  are  uniform  in  the  point  of 
their  being  the  repose  of  the  appetite  in  something  good: 
and  in  this  respect  pleasure  can  be  a  rule  or  measure. 
Because  that  man  is  good,  whose  will  rests  in  the  true  good : 
and  that  man  evil,  whose  will  rests  in  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Since  pleasure  perfects  operation  as  its 
end,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXIIL,  A.  4);  an  operation 
cannot  be  perfectly  good,  unless  there  be  also  pleasure  in 
good :  because  the  goodness  of  a  thing  depends  on  its  end. 
And  thus,  in  a  way,  the  goodness  of  the  pleasure  is  th(^, 
cause  of  goodness  in  the  operation. 


QUESTION  XXXV. 

OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF. 

{In  Eight  Articles.) 

We  have  now  to  consider  pain  and  sorrow:  concerning 
which  we  must  consider  (i)  Sorrow  or  pain  in  itself:  (2)  Its 
cause:  (3)  Its  effects:  (4)  Its  remedies:  (5)  Its  goodness  or 
malice. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  pain  is  a  passion  of  the  soul  ?  (2)  Whether 
sorrow  is  the  same  as  pain  ?  (3)  Whether  sorrow  or  pain 
is  contrary  to  pleasure  ?  (4)  Whether  all  sorrow  is  contrary 
to  all  pleasure  ?  (5)  Whether  there  is  a  sorrow  contrary  to 
the  pleasure  of  contemplation  ?  (6)  Whether  sorrow  is  to 
be  shunned  more  than  pleasure  is  to  be  sought  ?  (7)  Whether 
exterior  pain  is  greater  than  interior  ?  (8)  Of  the  species 
of  sorrow. 

First  Article, 
whether  pain  is  a  passion  of  the  soul  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  pain  is  not  a  passion  of  the 
soul.  Because  no  passion  of  the  soul  is  in  the  body.  But 
pain  can  be  in  the  body,  since  Augustine  says  {De  Vera 
Relig.  xii.),  that  bodily  pain  is  a  sudden  corruption  of  the 
well-being  of  that  thing  which  the  soul,  by  making  evil  use  of 
it,  made  subject  to  corruption.  Therefore  pain  is  not  a  passion 
of  the  soul. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  every  passion  of  the  soul  belongs  to  the 
appetitive  faculty.  But  pain  does  not  belong  to  the  appe- 
titive, but  rather  to  the  apprehensive  part:  for  Augustine 

404 


OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF  405 

says  (De  Nat.  Boni,  xxi.)  that  bodily  pain  is  caused  by  the 
sense  resisting  a  more  powerful  body.  Therefore  pain  is  not 
a  passion  of  the  soul. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  every  passion  of  the  soul  belongs  to  the 
animal  appetite.  But  pain  does  not  belong  to  the  animal 
appetite,  but  rather  to  the  natural  appetite:  for  Augustine 
says  (Gen.  ad  lit.  xiii.) :  Had  not  some  good  remained  in  nature, 
we  should  feel  no  pain  in  being  punished  by  the  loss  of  good. 
Therefore  pain  is  not  a  passion  of  the  soul. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  [De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  reckons  pain 
among  the  passions   of    the  soul;  quoting  Virgil    {Mneid, 

vi.  733) : 

"  Hence  wild  desires  and  grovelling  fears 

And  human  laughter,  human  tears." 

Trl.  CONINGTON. 

/  answer  that,  Just  as  two  things  are  requisite  for  pleasure; 
namely,  conjunction  with  good  and  perception  of  this  con- 
junction; so  also  two  things  are  requisite  for  pain;  namely, 
conjunction  with  some  evil  (which  is  in  so  far  evil  as  it 
deprives  one  of  some  good),  and  perception  of  this  conjunc- 
tion. Now  whatever  is  conjoined,  if  it  have  not  the  aspect 
of  good  or  evil  in  regard  to  the  being  to  which  it  is  con- 
joined, cannot  cause  pleasure  or  pain.  Whence  it  is  evident 
that  something  under  the  aspect  of  good  or  evil  is  the  object 
of  pleasure  or  pain.  But  good  and  evil,  as  such,  are  objects 
of  the  appetite.  Consequently  it  is  clear  that  pleasure  and 
pain  belong  to  the  appetite. 

Now  every  appetitive  movement  or  inclination  conse- 
quent to  apprehension,  belongs  to  the  intellective  or  sensi- 
tive appetite:  since  the  inclination  of  the  natural  appetite 
is  not  consequent  to  an  apprehension  of  the  subject  of  that 
appetite,  but  to  the  apprehension  of  another,  as  stated  in  the 
First  Part  (Q.  CIII.,  AA.  i,  3).  Since  then  pleasure  and 
pain  presuppose  some  sense  or  apprehension  in  the  same 
subject,  it  is  evident  that  pain,  like  pleasure,  is  in  the 
intellective  or  sensitive  appetite. 

Again  every  movement  of  the  sensitive  appetite  is  called 
a  passion,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXII.,  AA.  i,  3):  and  especi- 


4o6  QUESTION  XXXV 

ally  those  which  tend  to  some  defect.  Consequently  pain, 
according  as  it  is  in  the  sensitive  appetite,  is  most  properly 
called  a  passion  of  the  soul:  just  as  bodily  ailments  are 
properly  called  passions  of  the  body.  Hence  Augustine 
(De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  reckons  pain  especially  as  being  a  kind  of 
ailment. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  We  speak  of  pain  of  the  body,  because  the 
cause  of  pain  is  in  the  body :  as  when  we  suffer  something 
hurtful  to  the  body.  But  the  movement  of  pain  is  always 
in  the  soul;  since  the  body  cannot  feel  pain  unless  the  soul  feel 
it,  as  Augustine  says  on  Ps.  Ixxxvii.  4. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  We  speak  of  pain  of  the  senses,  not  as  though 
it  were  an  act  of  the  sensitive  power ;  but  because  the  senses 
are  required  for  bodily  pain,  in  the  same  way  as  for  bodily 
pleasure. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Pain  at  the  loss  of  good  proves  the  goodness 
of  the  nature,  not  because  pain  is  an  act  of  the  natural 
appetite,  but  because  nature  desires  something  as  good, 
the  removal  of  which  being  perceived,  there  results  the 
passion  of  pain  in  the  sensitive  appetite. 

Second  Article, 
whether  sorrow  is  the  same  as  pain  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  sorrow  is  not  pain.  For 
Augustine  says  [De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  that  pain  is  used  to  express 
bodily  suffering.  But  sorrow  is  used  more  in  reference  to 
the  soul.     Therefore  sorrow  is  not  pain. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  pain  is  only  in  respect  of  present  evil. 
But  sorrow  can  refer  to  both  past  and  future  evil:  thus 
repentance  is  sorrow  for  the  past,  and  anxiety  is  sorrow  for 
the  future.     Therefore  sorrow  is  quite  different  from  pain. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  pain  seems  not  to  follow  save  from  the 
sense  of  touch.  But  sorrow  can  arise  from  all  the  senses. 
Therefore  sorrow  is  not  pain,  and  extends  to  more  objects. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Rom.  ix.  2):  I  have 
great  sorrow  (Douay, — sadness)  and  continual  pain  (Douay, — 


OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF  407 

sorrow)  in  my  heart,  thus  denoting  the  same  thing  by  sorrow 
and  pain. 

I  answer  that,  Pleasure  and  pain  can  arise  from  a  twofold 
apprehension,  namely,  from  the  apprehension  of  an  exterior 
sense;  and  from  the  interior  apprehension  of  the  intellect 
or  of  the  imagination.  Now  the  interior  apprehension 
extends  to  more  objects  than  the  exterior  apprehension: 
because  whatever  things  come  under  the  exterior  appre- 
hension, come  under  the  interior,  but  not  conversely. 
Consequently  that  pleasure  alone  which  is  caused  by  an 
interior  apprehension  is  called  joy,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXI. 
A.  3) :  and  in  like  manner  that  pain  alone  which  is  caused 
by  an  interior  apprehension,  is  called  sorrow.  And  just 
as  that  pleasure  which  is  caused  by  an  exterior  apprehension, 
is  called  pleasure  but  not  joy;  so  too  that  pain  which  is 
caused  by  an  exterior  apprehension,  is  called  pain  indeed 
but  not  sorrow.  Accordingly  sorrow  is  a  kind  of  pain,  as 
joy  is  a  species  of  pleasure. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Augustine  is  speaking  there  of  the  use  of 
the  word:  because  pain  is  more  generally  used  in  reference 
to  bodily  pains,  which  are  better  known,  than  in  reference 
to  spiritual  pains. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  External  sense  perceives  only  what  is 
present;  but  the  interior  cognitive  power  can  perceive  the 
present,  past  and  future.  Consequently  sorrow  can  regard 
present,  past  and  future:  whereas  bodily  pain,  which  follows 
the  apprehension  of  the  external  sense,  can  only  regard 
something  present. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  sensibles  of  touch  are  painful,  not  only 
in  so  far  as  they  are  disproportionate  to  the  apprehensive 
power,  but  also  in  so  far  as  they  are  contrary  to  nature: 
whereas  the  objects  of  the  other  senses  can  indeed  be  dis- 
proportionate to  the  apprehensive  power,  but  they  are  not 
contrary  to  nature,  save  as  they  are  subordinate  to  the 
sensibles  of  touch.  Consequently  man  alone,  who  is  a 
perfectly  cognizant  animal,  takes  pleasure  in  the  objects 
of  the  other  senses  for  their  own  sake;  whereas  other 
animals  take  no  pleasure  in  them  save  as  referable  to  the 


4o8  QUESTION  XXXV 

sensibles  of  touch,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iii.  Accordingly,  in 
referring  to  the  objects  of  the  other  senses,  we  do  not  speak 
of  pain  in  so  far  as  it  is  contrary  to  natural  pleasure :  but 
rather  of  sorrow,  which  is  contrary  to  animal  joy. — So  then 
if  pain  be  taken  as  denoting  bodily  pain,  which  is  its  more 
usual  meaning,  then  it  is  contrasted  with  sorrow,  according 
to  the  distinction  of  interior  and  exterior  apprehension; 
although,  on  the  part  of  the  objects,  pleasure  extends  further 
than  does  bodily  pain.  But  if  pain  be  taken  in  a  wide  sense, 
then  it  is  the  genus  of  sorrow,  as  stated  above. 

Third  Article, 
whether  sorrow  or  pain  is  contrary  to  pleasure  ? 

We  'proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  sorrow  is  not  contrary  to 
pleasure.  For  one  of  two  contraries  is  not  the  cause  of  the 
other.  But  sorrow  can  be  the  cause  of  pleasure;  for  it  is 
written  (Matth.  v.  5):  Blessed  are  they  that  mourn,  for  they 
shall  he  comforted.  Therefore  they  are  not  contrary  to  one 
another. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  one  contrary  does  not  denominate  the 
other.  But  to  some,  pain  or  sorrow  gives  pleasure:  thus 
Augustine  says  {Conf.  iii.)  that  in  stage-plays  sorrow  itself 
gives  pleasure:  and  {ibid,  iv.)  that  weeping  is  a  bitter  thing, 
and  yet  it  sometimes  pleases  us.  Therefore  pain  is  not  con- 
trary to  pleasure. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  one  contrary  is  not  the  matter  of  the 
other;  because  contraries  cannot  co-exist  together.  But 
sorrow  can  be  the  matter  of  pleasure;  for  Augustine  says 
(De  Pcenit.  xiii.) :  The  penitent  should  ever  sorrow,  and  rejoice 
in  his  sorrow.  The  Philosopher  too  says  (Ethic,  ix.)  that, 
on  the  other  hand,  the  evil  man  feels  pain  at  having  been 
pleased.  Therefore  pleasure  and  pain  are  not  contrary  to 
one  another. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (De  Civ.  Dei)  that  joy 
is  the  volition  of  consent  to  the  things  we  wish  :  and  that  sorrow 
is  the  volition  of  dissent  to  the  things  we  do  not  wish.      But 


OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF  4^9 

consent  and  dissent  are  contraries.     Therefore  pleasure  and 
sorrow  are  contrary  to  one  another. 

/  answer  that,  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Meiaph.  x.),  con- 
trariety is  a  difference  in  respect  of  a  form.  Now  the  form 
or  species  of  a  passion  or  movement  is  taken  from  the  object 
or  term.  Consequently,  since  the  objects  of  pleasure  and 
sorrow  or  pain,  viz.,  present  good  and  present  evil,  are 
contrary  to  one  another,  it  follows  that  pain  and  pleasure 
are  contrary  to  one  another. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Nothing  hinders  one  contrary  causing  the 
other  accidentally:  and  thus  sorrow  can  be  the  cause  of 
pleasure.  In  one  way,  in  so  far  as  from  sorrow  at  the  absence 
of  something,  or  at  the  presence  of  its  contrary,  one  seeks 
the  more  eagerly  for  something  pleasant:  thus  a  thirsty 
man  seeks  more  eagerly  the  pleasure  of  a  drink,  as  a  remedy 
for  the  pain  that  he  suffers.  In  another  way,  in  so  far  as, 
from  a  strong  desire  for  a  certain  pleasure,  one  does  not 
shrink  from  undergoing  pain,  so  as  to  obtain  that  pleasure. 
In  each  of  these  ways,  the  sorrows  of  the  present  life  lead 
us  to  the  comfort  of  the  future  life.  Because  by  the  mere 
fact  that  man  mourns  for  his  sins,  or  for  the  delay  of  glory, 
he  merits  the  consolation  of  eternity.  In  like  manner  a 
man  merits  it  when  he  shrinks  not  from  hardships  and  straits 
in  order  to  obtain  it. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Sorrow  itself  can  be  pleasurable  accidentally 
in  so  far  as  it  is  accompanied  by  wonder,  as  in  stage-plays; 
or  in  so  far  as  it  recalls  a  beloved  object  to  one's  memory, 
and  makes  one  feel  one's  love  for  the  thing,  whose  absence 
gives  us  pain.  Consequently,  since  love  is  pleasant,  both 
pain  and  whatever  else  results  from  love,  forasmuch  as  they 
remind  us  of  our  love,  are  pleasant.  And,  for  this  reason, 
we  derive  pleasure  even  from  sorrows  depicted  on  the 
stage:  in  so  far  as,  in  witnessing  them,  we  perceive  our- 
selves to  conceive  a  certain  love  for  those  who  are  there 
represented. 

Reply,  Ohj.  3.  The  will  and  the  reason  reflect  on  their 
own  acts,  inasmuch  as  the  acts  themselves  of  the  will  and 
reason  are  considered  under  the  aspect  of  good  or  evil.     Tn 


410  QUESTION  XXXV 

this  way  sorrow  can  be  the  matter  of  pleasure,  or  vice  versa, 
not  essentially  but  accidentally :  that  is,  in  so  far  as  either  of 
them  is  considered  under  the  aspect  of  good  or  evil. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  all  sorrow  is  contrary  to  all  pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  all  sorrow  is  contrary  to  all 
pleasure.  Because,  just  as  whiteness  and  blackness  are 
contrary  species  of  colour,  so  pleasure  and  sorrow  are  contrary 
species  of  the  soul's  passions.  But  whiteness  and  blackness 
are  universally  contrary  to  one  another.  Therefore  pleasure 
and  sorrow  are  so  too. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  remedies  are  made  of  things  contrary 
(to  the  evil).  But  every  pleasure  is  a  remedy  for  all  manner 
of  sorrow,  as  the  Philosopher  declares  (Ethic,  vii.).  There- 
fore every  pleasure  is  contrary  to  every  sorrow. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  contraries  are  hindrances  to  one  another. 
But  every  sorrow  hinders  any  kind  of  pleasure :  as  is  evident 
from  Ethic,  x.  Therefore  every  sorrow  is  contrary  to 
every  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  The  same  thing  is  not  the  cause  of  con- 
traries. But  joy  for  one  thing,  and  sorrow  for  the  opposite 
thing,  proceed  from  the  same  habit:  thus  from  charity  it 
happens  that  we  rejoice  with  them  that  rejoice,  and  weep 
with  Mem  that  weep  (Rom.  xii.  15).  Therefore  not  every 
sorrow  is  contrary  to  every  pleasure. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  in  Metaph.  x.,  contrariety  is  a 
difference  in  respect  of  a  form.  Now  a  form  may  be  generic 
or  specific.  Consequently  things  may  be  contraries  in 
respect  of  a  generic  form,  as  virtue  and  vice;  or  in  respect 
of  a  specific  form,  as  justice  and  injustice. 

Now  we  must  observe  that  some  things  are  specified  by 
absolute  forms,  e.g.,  substances  and  qualities;  whereas 
other  things  are  specified  in  relation  to  something  extrinsic, 
e.g.,  passions  and  movements,  which  derive  their  species 
from  their  terms  or  objects.     Accordingly  in  those  things 


OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF  411 

that  are  specified  by  absolute  forms,  it  happens  that  species 
contained  under  contrary  genera  are  not  contrary  as  to 
their  specific  nature:  but  it  does  not  happen  for  them  to 
have  any  affinity  or  fittingness  to  one  another.  For  in- 
temperance and  justice,  which  are  in  the  contrary  genera  of 
virtue  and  vice,  are  not  contrary  to  one  another  in  respect 
of  their  specific  nature;  and  yet  they  have  no  affinity  or 
fittingness  to  one  another. — On  the  other  hand,  in  those 
things  that  are  specified  in  relation  to  something  extrinsic, 
it  happens  that  species  belonging  to  contrary  genera,  are 
not  only  not  contrary  to  one  another,  but  also  that  they 
have  a  certain  mutual  affinity  or  fittingness.  The  reason 
of  this  is  that  where  there  is  one  same  relation  to  two  con- 
traries, there  is  contrariety;  e.g.,  to  approach  to  a  white 
thing,  and  to  approach  to  a  black  thing,  are  contraries; 
whereas  contrary  relations  to  contrary  things,  implies  a 
certain  likeness,  e.g.,  to  recede  from  something  white,  and 
to  approach  to  something  black.  This  is  most  evident  in 
the  case  of  contradiction,  which  is  the  principle  of  opposition : 
because  opposition  consists  in  affirming  and  denying  the 
same  thing,  e.g.,  white  and  not-white  ;  while  there  is  fitting- 
ness and  likeness  in  the  afiirmation  of  one  contrary  and 
the  denial  of  the  other,  as,  if  I  were  to  say  black  and  not 
white. 

Now  sorrow  and  pleasure,  being  passions,  are  specified 
by  their  objects.  According  to  their  respective  genera, 
they  are  contrary  to  one  another:  since  one  is  a  kind  of 
pursuit,  the  other  a  kind  of  avoidance,  which  are  to  the 
appetite,  what  affirmation  and  denial  are  to  the  intellect 
{Ethic,  vi.).  Consequently  sorrow  and  pleasure  in  respect 
of  the  same  object,  are  specifically  contrary  to  one  another: 
whereas  sorrow  and  pleasure  in  respect  of  objects  that  are 
not  contrary  but  disparate,  are  not  specifically  contrary 
to  one  another,  but  are  also  disparate;  for  instance,  sorrow 
at  the  death  of  a  friend,  and  pleasure  in  contemplation. 
If,  however,  those  diverse  objects  be  contrary  to  one 
another,  then  pleasure  and  sorrow  are  not  only  specifically 
contrary,  but  they  also  have  a  certain  mutual  fittingness 


412  QUESTION  XXXV 

and  affinity:  for  instance  to  rejoice  in  good  and  to  sorrow 
for  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Whiteness  and  blackness  do  not  take  their 
species  from  their  relationship  to  something  extrinsic,  as 
pleasure  and  sorrow  do :  wherefore  the  comparison  does  not 
hold. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Genus  is  taken  from  matter,  as  is  stated  in 
Metaph.  viii. :  and  in  accidents  the  subject  takes  the  place 
of  matter.  Now  it  has  been  said  above  that  pleasure  and 
sorrow  are  generically  contrary  to  one  another.  Conse- 
quently in  every  sorrow  the  subject  has  a  disposition  con- 
trary to  the  disposition  of  the  subject  of  pleasure:  because 
in  every  pleasure  the  appetite  is  viewed  as  accepting  what  it 
possesses,  and  in  every  sorrow,  as  avoiding  it.  And  there- 
fore on  the  part  of  the  subject  every  pleasure  is  a  remedy 
for  any  kind  of  sorrow,  and  every  sorrow  is  a  hindrance  of  all 
manner  of  pleasure:  but  chiefly  when  pleasure  is  opposed 
to  sorrow  specifically. 

Wherefore  the  Reply  to  the  Third  Objection  is  evident. — 
Or  we  may  say  that,  although  not  every  sorrow  is  specific- 
ally contrary  to  every  pleasure,  yet  they  are  contrary  to 
one  another  in  regard  to  their  effects:  since  one  has  the 
effect  of  strengthening  the  animal  nature,  while  the  other 
results  in  a  kind  of  discomfort. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  there  is  any  sorrow  contrary  to  the 
pleasure  of  contemplation  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  is  a  sorrow  that  is  con- 
trary to  the  pleasure  of  contemplation.  For  the  Apostle 
says  (2  Cor.  vii.  10):  The  sorrow  that  is  according  to  God, 
worketh  penance  steadfast  unto  salvation.  Now  to  look  at 
God  belongs  to  the  higher  reason,  whose  act  is  to  give  itself 
to  contemplation,  according  to  Augustine  {De  Trin.  xii.). 
Therefore  there  is  a  sorrow  contrary  to  the  pleasure  of 
contemplation. 


OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF  413 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  contrary  things  have  contrary  effects. 
If  therefore  the  contemplation  of  one  contrary  gives  pleasure, 
the  other  contrary  will  give  sorrow :  and  so  there  will  be  a 
sorrow  contrary  to  the  pleasure  of  contemplation. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  as  the  object  of  pleasure  is  good,  so  the 
object  of  sorrow  is  evil.  But  contemplation  can  be  an  evil; 
since  the  Philosopher  says  {Metaph.  xii.)  that  it  is  wrong 
to  think  of  certain  things.  Therefore  sorrow  can  be  contrary 
to  the  pleasure  of  contemplation. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  any  work,  so  far  as  it  is  unhindered,  can 
be  an  object  of  pleasure,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  vii.  and  x.  But 
the  work  of  contemplation  can  be  hindered  in  many  ways, 
either  so  as  to  destroy  it  altogether,  or  so  as  to  make  it 
dif&cult.  Therefore  in  contemplation  there  can  be  a  sorrow 
contrary  to  the  pleasure. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  affliction  of  the  flesh  is  a  cause  of  sorrow. 
But,  as  it  is  written  (Eccles.  xii,  12)  much  study  is  an  affliction 
of  the  flesh.  Therefore  contemplation  admits  of  sorrow 
contrary  to  its  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Wis.  viii.  16):  Her,  i.e., 
wisdom's,  conversation  hath  no  bitterness,  nor  her  company 
any  tediousness  ;  but  joy  and  gladness.  Now  the  conversa- 
tion and  company  of  wisdom  are  found  in  contemplation. 
Therefore  there  is  no  sorrow  contrary  to  the  pleasure  of 
contemplation. 

/  answer  that.  The  pleasure  of  contemplation  can  be 
understood  in  two  ways.  In  one  way,  so  that  contemplation 
is  the  cause,  but  not  the  object  of  pleasure :  and  then  pleasure 
is  taken  not  in  contemplating  but  in  the  thing  contem- 
plated. Now  it  is  possible  to  contemplate  something  harm- 
ful and  sorrowful,  just  as  to  contemplate  something  suitable 
and  pleasant.  Consequently  if  the  pleasure  of  contempla- 
tion be  taken  in  this  way,  nothing  hinders  some  sorrow  being 
contrary  to  the  pleasure  of  contemplation. 

In  another  way,  the  pleasure  of  contemplation  is  under- 
stood, so  that  contemplation  is  its  object  and  cause;  as 
when  one  takes  pleasure  in  the  very  act  of  contemplating. 
And  thus,   according  to   Gregory  of    Nyssa   (Nemesius, — 


414    '  QUESTION  XXXV 

De  Nat.  Horn,  xviii.),  no  sorrow  is  contrary  to  that  pleasure 
which  is  about  contemplation  :  and  the  Philosopher  says  the 
same  (Topic,  i.,  and  Ethic,  x.).  This,  however,  is  to  be 
understood  as  being  the  case  properly  speaking.  The  reason 
is  because  sorrow  is  of  itself  contrary  to  pleasure  in  a 
contrary  object:  thus  pleasure  in  heat  is  contrary  to  sorrow 
caused  by  cold.  But  there  is  no  contrary  to  the  object  of 
contemplation:  because  contraries,  as  apprehended  by  the 
mind,  are  not  contrary,  but  one  is  the  means  of  knowing  the 
other.  Wherefore,  properly  speaking,  there  cannot  be  a 
sorrow  contrary  to  the  pleasure  of  contemplation. — Nor 
has  it  any  sorrow  annexed  to  it,  as  bodily  pleasures  have, 
which  are  like  remedies  against  certain  annoyances;  thus 
a  man  takes  pleasure  in  drinking  through  being  troubled 
with  thirst,  but  when  the  thirst  is  quite  driven  out,  the 
pleasure  of  drinking  ceases  also.  Because  the  pleasure  of 
contemplation  is  not  caused  by  one's  being  quit  of  an  annoy- 
ance, but  by  the  fact  that  contemplation  is  pleasant  in 
itself:  for  pleasure  is  not  a  becoming  but  a  perfect  operation, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXI.,  A.  i). 

Accidentally,  however,  sorrow  is  mingled  with  the  pleasure 
of  apprehension ;  and  this  in  two  ways :  first,  on  the  part  of 
an  organ,  secondly,  through  some  impediment  in  the  appre- 
hension. On  the  part  of  an  organ,  sorrow  or  pain  is  mingled 
with  apprehension,  directly,  as  regards  the  apprehensive 
powers  of  the  sensitive  part,  which  have  a  bodily  organ ; — 
either  from  the  sensible  object  disagreeing  with  the  normal 
condition  of  the  organ,  as  the  taste  of  something  bitter, 
and  the  smell  of  something  foul; — ^or  from  the  sensible 
object,  though  agreeable,  being  so  continuous  in  its  action 
on  the  sense,  that  it  exceeds  the  normal  condition  of  the 
organ,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXIII.,  A.  2),  the  result  being 
that  an  apprehension  which  at  first  was  pleasant  becomes 
tedious. — But  these  two  things  cannot  occur  directly  in  the 
contemplation  of  the  mind;  because  the  mind  has  no 
corporeal  organ:  wherefore  it  was  said  in  the  authority 
quoted  above  that  intellectual  contemplation  has  neither 
bitterness,    nor    tediousness.     Since,    however,    the    human 


OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF  4i5 

mind,  in  contemplation,  makes  use  of  the  sensitive  powers 
of  apprehension,  to  whose  acts  weariness  is  incidental; 
therefore  some  affliction  or  pain  is  indirectly  mingled  with 
contemplation. 

Nevertheless,  in  neither  of  these  ways,  is  the  pain  thus 
accidentally  mingled  with  contemplation,  contrary  to  the 
pleasure  thereof.  Because  pain  caused  by  a  hindrance  to 
contemplation,  is  not  contrary  to  the  pleasure  of  con- 
templation, but  rather  is  in  afhnity  and  in  harmony  with  it, 
as  is  evident  from  what  has  been  said  above  (A.  4):  while 
pain  or  sorrow  caused  by  bodily  weariness,  does  not  belong 
to  the  same  genus,  wherefore  it  is  altogether  disparate. 
Accordingly  it  is  evident  that  no  sorrow  is  contrary  to 
pleasure  taken  in  the  very  act  of  contemplation ;  nor  is  any 
sorrow  connected  with  it  save  accidentally. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  sorrow  which  is  according  to  God,  is  not 
caused  by  the  very  act  of  intellectual  contemplation,  but 
by  something  which  the  mind  contemplates:  viz.,  by  sin, 
which  the  mind  considers  as  contrary  to  the  love  of  God. 

Reply  Ohj,  2.  Things  which  are  contrary  according  to 
nature  are  not  contrary  according  as  they  exist  in  the  mind : 
for  things  that  are  contrary  in  reality  are  not  contrary  in 
the  order  of  thought;  indeed  rather  is  one  contrary  the 
reason  for  knowing  the  other.  Hence  one  and  the  same 
science  considers  contraries. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Contemplation,  in  itself,  is  never  evil,  since 
it  is  nothing  else  than  the  consideration  of  truth,  which  is 
the  good  of  the  intellect :  it  can,  however,  be  evil  accidentally, 
i.e.,  in  so  far  as  the  contemplation  of  a  less  noble  object 
hinders  the  contemplation  of  a  more  noble  object;  or  on 
the  part  of  the  object  contemplated,  to  which  the  appetite 
is  inordinately  attached. 

Reply  Ohj.  /\.  Sorrow  caused  by  a  hindrance  to  contempla- 
tion, is  not  contrary  to  the  pleasure  of  contemplation,  but 
is  in  harmony  with  it,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  5.  Affliction  of  the  flesh  affects  contemplation 
accidentally  and  indirectly,  as  stated  above. 


4i6  QUESTION  XXXV 


Sixth  Article. 

whether  sorrow  is  to  be  shunned  more  than 
pleasure  is  to  be  sought  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — ■ 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  sorrow  is  to  be  shunned  more 
than  pleasure  is  to  be  sought.  For  Augustine  says  (Qq.  83) : 
There  is  nobody  that  does  not  shun  sorrow  more  than  he  seeks 
pleasure.  Now  that  which  all  agree  in  doing,  seems  to  be 
natural.  Therefore  it  is  natural  and  right  for  sorrow  to 
be  shunned  more  than  pleasure  is  sought. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  action  of  a  contrary  conduces  to 
rapidity  and  intensity  of  movement :  for  hot  water  freezes 
quicker  and  harder  {Meteor,  i.).  But  the  shunning  of  sorrow 
is  due  to  the  contrariety  of  the  cause  of  sorrow ;  whereas  the 
desire  for  pleasure  does  not  arise  from  any  contrariety,  but 
rather  from  the  suitableness  of  the  pleasant  object.  There- 
fore sorrow  is  shunned  more  eagerly  than  pleasure  is  sought. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  stronger  the  passion  which  a  man 
resists  according  to  reason,  the  more  worthy  is  he  of  praise, 
and  the  more  virtuous:  since  virtue  is  concerned  with  the 
difficult  and  the  good  {Ethic,  ii.).  But  the  brave  man  who 
resists  the  movement  of  shunning  sorrow,  is  more  virtuous 
than  the  temperate  man,  who  resists  the  movement  of 
desire  for  pleasure:  since  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.) 
that  the  brave  and  the  just  are  chiefly  praised.  Therefore  the 
movement  of  shunning  sorrow  is  more  eager  than  the 
movement  of  seeking  pleasure. 

On  the  contrary,  Good  is  stronger  than  evil,  as  Dionysius 
declares  {Div.  Nom.  iv.).  But  pleasure  is  desirable  for  the 
sake  of  the  good  which  is  its  object;  whereas  the  shunning 
of  sorrow  is  on  account  of  evil.  Therefore  the  desire  for 
pleasure  is  more  eager  than  the  shunning  of  sorrow. 

/  answer  that,  The  desire  for  pleasure  is  of  itself  more 
eager  than  the  shunning  of  sorrow.  The  reason  of  this  is 
that  the  cause  of  pleasure  is  a  suitable  good;  while  the 
cause  of  pain  or  sorrow  is  an  unsuitable  evil.     Now  it 


OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF  417 

happens  that  a  certain  good  is  suitable  without  any  repug- 
nance at  all:  but  it  is  not  possible  for  any  evil  to  be  so 
unsuitable  as  not  to  be  suitable  in  some  way.  Wherefore 
pleasure  can  be  entire  and  perfect :  whereas  sorrow  is  always 
partial.  Therefore  desire  for  pleasure  is  naturally  greater 
than  the  shunning  of  sorrow. — Another  reason  is  because 
the  good,  which  is  the  object  of  pleasure,  is  sought  for  its 
own  sake:  whereas  the  evil,  which  is  the  object  of  sorrow, 
is  to  be  shunned  as  being  a  privation  of  good:  and  that 
which  is  by  reason  of  itself  is  stronger  than  that  which  is 
by  reason  of  something  else. — Moreover  we  find  a  con- 
firmation of  this  in  natural  movements.  For  every  natural 
movement  is  more  intense  in  the  end,  when  a  thing  approaches 
the  term  that  is  suitable  to  its  nature,  than  at  the  beginning, 
when  it  leaves  the  term  that  is  unsuitable  to  its  nature: 
as  though  nature  were  more  eager  in  tending  to  what  is  suit- 
able to  it,  than  in  shunning  what  is  unsuitable.  Therefore 
the  inclination  of  the  appetitive  power  is,  of  itself,  more 
eager  in  tending  to  pleasure  than  in  shunning  sorrow. 

But  it  happens  accidentally  that  a  man  shuns  sorrow 
more  eagerly  than  he  seeks  pleasure:  and  this  for  three 
reasons.  First,  on  the  part  of  the  apprehension.  Because, 
as  Augustine  says  {De  Trin.  x.),  love  is  felt  more  keenly,  when 
we  lack  that  which  we  love.  Now  from  the  lack  of  what  we 
love,  sorrow  results,  which  is  caused  either  by  the  loss  of 
some  loved  good,  or  by  the  presence  of  some  contrary  evil. 
But  pleasure  suffers  no  lack  of  the  good  loved,  for  it  rests 
in  possession  of  it.  Since  then  love  is  the  cause  of  pleasure 
and  sorrow,  the  latter  is  the  more  shunned,  according  as 
love  is  the  more  keenly  felt  on  account  of  that  which  is 
contrary  to  it. — -Secondly,  on  the  part  of  the  cause  of  sorrow 
or  pain,  which  cause  is  repugnant  to  a  good  that  is  more 
loved  than  the  good  in  -which  we  take  pleasure.  For  we 
love  the  natural  well-being  of  the  body  more  than  the 
pleasure  of  eating:  and  consequently  we  would  leave  the 
pleasure  of  eating  and  the  like,  from  fear  of  the  pain  occa- 
sioned by  blows  or  other  such  causes,  which  are  contrary  to 
the  well-being  of  the  body. ^Thirdly,  on  the  part  of  the 

II.  I  27 


4i8  QUESTION  XXXV 

effect:  namely,  in  so  far  as  sorrow  hinders  not  only  one 
pleasure,  but  all. 

Refly  Ohj.  i.  The  saying  of  Augustine  that  sorrow  is 
shunned  more  than  pleasure  is  sought  is  true  accidentally 
but  not  simply.  And  this  is  clear  from  what  he  says  after : 
Since  we  see  that  the  most  savage  animals  are  deterred  from 
the  greatest  pleasures  by  fear  of  fain,  which  pain  is  contrary 
to  life  which  is  loved  above  all. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  It  is  not  the  same  with  movement  from 
within  and  movement  from  without.  For  movement  from 
within  tends  to  what  is  suitable  more  than  it  recedes  from 
that  which  is  unsuitable ;  as  we  remarked  above  in  regard  to 
natural  movement.  But  movement  from  without  is  intensi- 
fied by  the  very  opposition:  because  each  thing  strives  in 
its  own  way  to  resist  anything  contrary  to  it,  as  aiming  at 
its  own  preservation.  Hence  violent  movement  is  intense 
at  first,  and  slackens  towards  the  end. — Now  the  movement 
of  the  appetitive  faculty  is  from  within :  since  it  tends  from 
the  soul  to  the  object.  Consequently  pleasure  is,  of  itself, 
more  to  be  sought  than  sorrow  is  to  be  shunned.  But  the 
movement  of  the  sensitive  faculty  is  from  without,  as  it 
were  from  the  object  to  the  soul.  Consequently  the  more 
contrary  a  thing  is  the  more  it  is  felt.  And  then  too,  acci- 
dentally, in  so  far  as  the  senses  are  requisite  for  pleasure 
and  pain,  pain  is  shunned  more  than  pleasure  is  sought. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  A  brave  man  is  praised,  not  from  the  fact 
that,  in  accordance  with  reason,  he  is  not  overcome  by  any 
kind  of  sorrow  or  pain,  but  by  that  which  is  consistent  with 
the  danger  of  death.  And  this  kind  of  sorrow  is  more 
shunned,  than  pleasures  of  the  table  or  of  sexual  intercourse 
are  to  be  sought,  which  latter  pleasures  are  the  object  of 
temperance:  thus  life  is  loved  more  than  food  and  sexual 
pleasure.  But  the  temperate  man  is  praised  for  refraining 
from  pleasures  of  touch,  more  than  for  shunning  the  pains 
which  are  contrary  to  them,  as  is  stated  in  Ethic,  iii. 


OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF  419 


Seventh  Article, 
whether  outward  pain  is  greater  than  interior 

SORROW  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — ■ 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  outward  pain  is  greater  than 
interior  sorrow  of  the  heart.  Because  outward  pain  arises 
from  a  cause  repugnant  to  the  well-being  of  the  body  in 
which  is  life :  whereas  interior  sorrow  is  caused  by  some  evil 
in  the  imagination.  Since,  therefore,  life  is  loved  more 
than  an  imagined  good,  it  seems  that,  according  to  what 
has  been  said  above  (A.  6),  outward  pain  is  greater  than 
interior  sorrow. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  reality  moves  more  than  its  likeness 
does.  But  outward  pain  arises  from  the  real  conjunction 
of  some  contrary:  whereas  inward  sorrow  arises  from  the 
apprehended  likeness  of  a  contrary.  Therefore  outward 
pain  is  greater  than  inward  sorrow. 

Ob].  3.  Further,  a  cause  is  known  by  its  effect.  But  out- 
ward pain  has  more  striking  effects:  since  man  dies  sooner 
of  outward  pain  than  of  interior  sorrow.  Therefore  outward 
pain  is  greater  and  is  shunned  more  than  interior  sorrow. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Ecclus.  xxv.  17) :  The  sadness 
of  the  heart  is  every  wound  (Douay, — plague),  and  the  wicked- 
ness of  a  woman  is  all  evil.  Therefore,  just  as  the  wicked- 
ness of  a  woman  surpasses  all  other  wickedness,  as  the  text 
implies;  so  sadness  of  the  heart  surpasses  every  outward 
wound. 

I  answer  that,  Interior  and  exterior  pain  agree  in  one  point, 
and  differ  in  two.  They  agree  in  this,  that  each  is  a  move- 
ment of  the  appetitive  power,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  But 
they  differ  in  respect  of  those  two  things  which  are  requisite 
for  pain  and  pleasure;  namely,  in  respect  of  the  cause, 
which  is  a  conjoined  good  or  evil;  and  in  respect  of  the 
apprehension.  For  the  cause  of  outward  pain  is  a  conjoined 
evil  repugnant  to  the  body :  while  the  cause  of  inward  pain 
is    a   conjoined   evil   repugnant   to   the   appetite.     Again, 


420  QUESTION  XXXV 

outward  pain  arises  from  an  apprehension  of  sense,  chiefly 
of  touch;  while  inward  pain  arises  from  an  interior  appre- 
hension, of  the  imagination  or  of  the  reason. 

If  then  we  compare  the  cause  of  inward  pain  to  the  cause 
of  outward  pain,  the  former  belongs,  of  itself,  to  the  appetite 
to  which  both  these  pains  belong:  while  the  latter  belongs 
to  the  appetite  indirectly.  Because  inward  pain  arises  from 
something  being  repugnant  to  the  appetite  itself,  while 
outward  pain  arises  from  something  being  repugnant  to  the 
appetite,  through  being  repugnant  to  the  body.  Now,  that 
which  is  of  itself  is  always  prior  to  that  which  is  by  reason 
of  another.  Wherefore,  from  this  point  of  view,  inward 
pain  surpasses  outward  pain. — In  like  manner  also  on  the 
part  of  apprehension:  because  the  apprehension  of  reason 
and  imagination  is  of  a  higher  order  than  the  apprehension 
of  the  sense  of  touch. — Consequently  inward  pain  is,  simply 
and  of  itself,  more  keen  than  outward  pain :  a  sign  whereof 
is  that  one  willingly  undergoes  outward  pain  in  order  to 
avoid  inward  pain:  and  in  so  far  as  outward  pain  is  not 
repugnant  to  the  interior  appetite,  it  becomes  in  a  manner 
pleasant  and  agreeable  by  way  of  inward  joy.  Sometimes, 
however,  outward  pain  is  accompanied  by  inward  pain,  and 
then  the  pain  is  increased.  Because  inward  pain  is  not 
only  greater  than  outward  pain,  it  is  also  more  universal: 
since  whatever  is  repugnant  to  the  body,  can  be  repugnant 
to  the  interior  appetite;  and  whatever  is  apprehended  by 
sense  may  be  apprehended  by  imagination  and  reason,  but 
not  conversely.  Hence  in  the  passage  quoted  above  it  is 
said  expressively:  Sadness  of  the  heart  is  every  wound, 
because  even  the  pains  of  outward  wounds  are  comprised 
in  the  interior  sorrows  of  the  heart. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Inward  pain  can  also  arise  from  things  that 
are  destructive  of  life.  And  then  the  comparison  of  inward 
to  outward  pain  must  not  be  taken  in  reference  to  the 
various  evils  that  cause  pain;  but  in  regard  to  the  various 
ways  in  which  this  cause  of  pain  is  compared  to  the  appetite. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Inward  pain  is  not  caused  by  the  appre- 
hended likeness  of  a  thing :  for  a  man  is  not  inwardly  pained 


OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF  421 

by  the  apprehended  likeness  itself,  but  by  the  thing  which 
the  likeness  represents.  And  this  thing  is  all  the  more 
perfectly  apprehended  by  means  of  its  likeness,  as  this  like- 
ness is  more  immaterial  and  abstract.  Consequently  inward 
pain  is,  of  itself,  greater,  as  being  caused  by  a  greater  evil,  for- 
asmuch as  evil  is  better  known  by  an  inward  apprehension. 
Reply  Ohj.  3.  Bodily  changes  are  more  liable  to  be  caused 
by  outward  pain,  both  from  the  fact  that  outward  pain  is 
caused  by  a  corruptive  conjoined  corporally,  which  is  a 
necessary  condition  of  the  sense  of  touch;  and  from  the  fact 
that  the  outward  sense  is  more  material  than  the  inward 
sense,  just  as  the  sensitive  appetite  is  more  material  than 
the  intellective.  For  this  reason,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXII . 
A.  3;  Q.  XXXI.,  A.  5),  the  body  undergoes  a  greater  change 
from  the  movement  of  the  sensitive  appetite :  and,  in  like 
manner,  from  outward  than  from  inward  pain. 

Eighth  Article, 
whether  there  are  only  four  species  of  sorrow  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  Damascene's  {De  Fide  Or- 
thod.  ii.)  division  of  sorrow  into  four  species  is  incorrect; 
viz.,  into  torpor,  distress,  which  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Neme- 
sius, — De  Nat.  Horn,  xix.)  calls  anxiety,' — pity,  and  envy. 
For  sorrow  is  contrary  to  pleasure.  But  there  are  not  several 
species  of  pleasure.  Therefore  it  is  incorrect  to  assign 
different  species  of  sorrow. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Repentance  is  a  species  of  sorrow;  and  so 
are  indignation  and  jealousy,  as  the  Philosopher  states 
(Rhet.  ii.).  But  these  are  not  included  in  the  above 
species.     Therefore  this  division  is  insufficient. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  members  of  a  division  should  be 
things  that  are  opposed  to  one  another.  But  these  species 
are  not  opposed  to  one  another.  For  according  to  Gregory 
(Nemesius, — loc.  cit.)  torpor  is  sorrow  depriving  of  speech  : 
anxiety  is  the  sorrow  that  weighs  down  ;  envy  is  sorrow  for 
another's  good  ;  pity  is  sorrow  for  another^ s  wrongs.     But  it 


422  QUESTION  XXXV 

is  possible  for  one  to  sorrow  for  another's  wrongs,  and  for 
another's  good,  and  at  the  same  time  to  be  weighed  down 
inwardly,  and  outwardly  to  be  speechless.  Therefore  this 
division  is  incorrect. 

On  the  contrary  stands  the  twofold  authority  of  Gregory 
of  Nyssa  and  of  Damascene. 

/  answer  that,  It  belongs  to  the  notion  of  a  species  that 
it  is  something  added  to  the  genus.  But  a  thing  can  be 
added  to  a  genus  in  two  ways.  First,  as  something  belong- 
ing of  itself  to  the  genus,  and  virtually  contained  therein: 
thus  rational  is  added  to  animal.  Such  an  addition  makes 
true  species  of  a  genus :  as  the  Philosopher  says  (Metaph.  vii, 
viii.).  But,  secondly,  a  thing  may  be  added  to  a  genus, 
that  is,  as  it  were,  foreign  to  the  notion  conveyed  by  that 
genus:  thus  white  or  something  of  the  kind  may  be  added 
to  animal.  Such  an  addition  does  not  make  true  species  of 
the  genus,  according  to  the  usual  sense  in  which  we  speak 
of  genera  and  species.  But  sometimes  a  thing  is  said  to 
be  a  species  of  a  certain  genus,  through  having  something 
foreign  to  that  genus  indeed,  but  to  which  the  notion  of 
that  genus  is  applicable:  thus  a  live  coal  or  a  flame  is  said 
to  be  a  species  of  fire,  because  in  each  of  them  the  nature 
of  fire  is  applied  to  a  foreign  matter.  In  like  manner  we 
speak  of  astronomy  and  perspective  as  being  species  of 
mathematics,  inasmuch  as  the  principles  of  mathematics 
are  applied  to  natural  matter. 

In  accordance  with  this  manner  of  speaking,  the  species 
of  sorrow  are  reckoned  by  an  application  of  the  notion  of 
sorrow  to  something  foreign  to  it.  This  foreign  matter  may 
be  taken  on  the  part  of  the  cause  or  the  object,  or  of  the 
effect.  For  the  proper  object  of  sorrow  is  one^s  own  evil. 
Hence  sorrow  may  be  concerned  for  an  object  foreign  to  it 
either  through  one's  being  sorry  for  an  evil  that  is  not  one's 
own;  and  thus  we  have  pity  which  is  sorrow  for  another's 
evil,  considered,  however,  as  one's  own: — or  through  one's 
being  sorry  for  something  that  is  neither  evil  nor  one's 
own,  but  another's  good,  considered,  however,  as  one's  own 
evil:  and  thus  we  have  envy. — ^The  proper  effect  of  sorrow 


OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW,  IN  ITSELF  423 

consists  in  a  certain  iiight  of  the  appetite.  Wherefore  the 
foreign  element  in  the  effect  of  sorrow,  may  be  taken  so  as 
to  affect  the  first  part  only,  by  excluding  flight:  and  thus 
we  have  anxiety  which  weighs  on  the  mind,  so  as  to  make 
escape  seem  impossible :  hence  it  is  also  called  perplexity. 
If,  however,  the  mind  be  weighed  down  so  much,  that  even 
the  limbs  become  motionless,  which  belongs  to  torpor,  then 
we  have  the  foreign  element  affecting  both,  since  there  is 
neither  flight,  nor  is  the  effect  in  the  appetite.  And  the 
reason  why  torpor  especially  is  said  to  deprive  one  of  speech 
is  because  of  all  the  external  movements  the  voice  is  the 
best  expression  of  the  inward  thought  and  desire,  not  only 
in  men,  but  also  in  other  animals,  as  is  stated  in  Polit.  i. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Pleasure  is  caused  by  good,  which  has  only 
one  meaning:  and  so  pleasure  is  not  divided  into  several 
species  as  sorrow  is;  for  the  latter  is  caused  by  evil,  which 
happens  in  many  ways,  as  Dionysius  says  (Div.  Nom.  iv.). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Repentance  is  for  one's  own  evil,  which  is 
the  proper  object  of  sorrow:  wherefore  it  does  not  belong  to 
these  species. — Jealousy  and  indignation  are  included  in 
envy,  as  we  shall  explain  later  (II. -II.,  Q.  XXXVI.,  A.  2). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  division  is  not  according  to  opposite 
species;  but  according  to  the  diversity  of  foreign  matter 
to  which  the  notion  of  sorrow  is  applied,  as  stated  above. 


QUESTION  XXXVI. 

OF  THE  CAUSES  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN. 

[In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  causes  of  sorrow:  under  which 
head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  sorrow 
is  caused  by  the  loss  of  a  good  or  rather  by  the  presence  of 
an    evil  ?     (2)  Whether    desire    is    a    cause    of    sorrow  ? 

(3)  Whether  the  craving  for  unity  is  a  cause  of  sorrow  ? 

(4)  Whether  an  irresistible  power  is  a  cause  of  sorrow  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  sorrow  is  caused  by  the  loss  of  good  or  by 
the  presence  of  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  sorrow  is  caused  by  the  loss  of 
a  good  rather  than  by  the  presence  of  an  evil.  For  Augus- 
tine says  {De  VIII.  Qq.  Dulcit.  i.)  that  sorrow  is  caused  by 
the  loss  of  temporal  goods.  Therefore,  in  like  manner, 
every  sorrow  is  caused  by  the  loss  of  some  good. 

Ob].  2.  Further,  it  was  said  above  (Q.  XXXV.,  A.  4)  that 
the  sorrow,  which  is  contrary  to  a  pleasure,  has  the  same 
object  as  that  pleasure.  But  the  object  of  pleasure  is 
good,  as  stated  above  {Q.  XXIII.,  A.  4;  Q.  XXXI.,  A.  i; 
Q.  XXXV.,  A.  3).  Therefore  sorrow  is  caused  chiefly  by 
the  loss  of  good. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  according  to  Augustine  {De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.), 
love  is  the  cause  of  sorrow,  as  of  the  other  emotions  of  the 
soul.     But  the  object  of  love  is  good.     Therefore  pain  or 

424 


OF  THE  CAUSES  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN       425 

sorrow  is  felt  for  the  loss  of  good  rather  than  for  an  evil 
that  is  present. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that 
the  dreaded  evil  gives  rise  to  fear,  the  present  evil  is  the  cause 
of  sorrow. 

I  answer  that,  If  privations,  as  considered  by  the  mind, 
were  what  they  are  in  reality,  this  question  would  seem  to 
be  of  no  importance.  For,  as  stated  in  the  First  Part 
(Q.  XIV.,  A.  10;  Q.  XLVIIL,  A.  3),  evil  is  the  privation  of 
good :  and  privation  is  in  reality  nothing  else  than  the  lack 
of  the  contrary  habit;  so  that,  in  this  respect,  to  sorrow  for 
the  loss  of  good,  would  be  the  same  as  to  sorrow  for  the 
presence  of  evil. — -But  sorrow  is  a  movement  of  the  appetite 
in  consequence  of  an  apprehension:  and  even  a  privation, 
as  apprehended,  has  the  aspect  of  a  being,  wherefore  it  is 
called  a  being  of  reason  :  and  such  is  evil,  considered  as  a 
privation.  Accordingly,  so  far  as  the  movement  of  the  appe- 
tite is  concerned,  the  question  differs  as  to  which  of  the  two 
it  regards  chiefly,  the  present  evil  or  the  good  which  is  lost. 

Again,  since  the  movement  of  the  animal  appetite  holds 
the  same  place  in  the  actions  of  the  soul,  as  natural  move- 
ment in  natural  things;  the  truth  of  the  matter  is  to  be 
found  by  considering  natural  movements.  For  if,  in  natural 
movements,  we  observe  those  of  approach  and  withdrawal, 
approach  is  of  itself  directed  to  something  suitable  to  nature ; 
while  withdrawal  is  of  itself  directed  to  something  con- 
trary to  nature:  thus  a  heavy  body,  of  itself,  withdraws 
from  a  higher  place,  and  approaches  naturally  to  a  lower 
place.  But  if  we  consider  the  cause  of  both  these  move- 
ments, viz.,  gravity,  then  gravity  itself  inclines  towards  the 
lower  place  more  than  it  withdraws  from  the  higher  place, 
since  withdrawal  from  the  latter  is  the  reason  for  its  down- 
ward tendency. 

Accordingly,  since,  in  the  movements  of  the  appetite, 
sorrow  is  a  kind  of  flight  or  withdrawal,  while  pleasure  is 
a  kind  of  pursuit  or  approach;  just  as  pleasure  regards  first 
the  good  possessed,  as  its  proper  object,  so  sorrow  regards 
the  evil  that  is  present.     On  the  other  hand  love,  which  is 


426  QUESTION  XXXVI 

the  cause  of  pleasure  and  sorrow,  regards  good  rather  than 
evil:  and  therefore,  forasmuch  as  the  object  is  the  cause  of 
a  passion,  the  present  evil  is  more  properly  the  cause  of 
sorrow  or  pain,  than  the  good  which  is  lost. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  loss  itself  of  good  is  apprehended  as  an 
evil,  just  as  the  loss  of  evil  is  apprehended  as  a  good:  and  in 
this  sense  Augustine  says  that  pain  results  from  the  loss  of 
temporal  goods. 

Reply  Ohj,  2.  Pleasure  and  its  contrary  pain  have  the 
same  object,  but  under  contrary  aspects:  because  if  the 
presence  of  a  particular  thing  be  the  object  of  pleasure,  the 
absence  of  that  same  thing  is  the  object  of  sorrow.  Now 
one  contrary  includes  the  privation  of  the  other,  as  stated 
in  Metaph.  x. :  and  consequently  sorrow  in  respect  of  one 
contrary,  is,  in  a  way,  directed  to  the  same  thing  under  a 
contrary  aspect. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  When  many  movements  arise  from  one 
cause,  it  does  not  follow  that  they  all  regard  chiefly  that 
which  the  cause  regards  chiefly,  but  only  the  first  of  them. 
And  each  of  the  others  regards  chiefly  that  which  is  suitable 
to  it  according  to  its  own  nature. 

Second  Article, 
whether  desire  is  a  cause  of  sorrow  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  desire  is  not  a  cause  of  pain  or 
sorrow.  Because  sorrow  of  itself  regards  evil,  as  stated 
above  (A.  i):  whereas  desire  is  a  movement  of  the  appetite 
towards  good.  Now  movement  towards  one  contrary  is  not 
a  cause  of  the  movement  towards  the  other  contrary. 
Therefore  desire  is  not  a  cause  of  pain. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  pain,  according  to  Damascene  (De  Fide 
Orthod.  ii.),  is  caused  by  something  present;  whereas  the 
object  of  desire  is  something  future.  Therefore  desire  is  not 
a  cause  of  pain. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  that  which  is  pleasant  in  itself  is  not 
a  cause  of  pain.     But  desire  is  pleasant  in  itself,  as  the 


OF  THE  CAUSES  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN        427 

Philosopher   says   {Rhet.   i.)-      Therefore    desire    is   not   a 
cause  of  pain  or  sorrow. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Enchirid.  xxiv.):  When 
ignorance  of  things  necessary  to  be  done,  and  desire  of  things 
hurtful,  found  their  way  in  ;  error  and  fain  stole  an  entrance 
in  their  company.  But  ignorance  is  the  cause  of  error. 
Therefore  desire  is  a  cause  of  sorrow. 

/  answer  that,  Sorrow  is  a  movement  of  the  animal  appe- 
tite. Now,  as  stated  above  (A.  i)  the  appetitive  movement 
is  likened  to  the  natural  appetite;  a  likeness,  that  may  be 
assigned  to  a  twofold  cause;  one,  on  the  part  of  the  end, 
the  other,  on  the  part  of  the  principle  of  movement.  Thus, 
on  the  part  of  the  end,  the  cause  of  a  heavy  body's  downward 
movement  is  the  lower  place;  while  the  principle  of  that 
movement  is  a  natural  inclination  resulting  from  gravity. 

Now  the  cause  of  the  appetitive  movement,  on  the  part 
of  the  end,  is  the  object  of  that  movement.  And  thus,  it 
has  been  said  above  (A.  i)  that  the  cause  of  pain  or  sorrow 
is  a  present  evil. — On  the  other  hand,  the  cause,  by  way  of 
principle,  of  that  movement,  is  the  inward  inclination  of 
the  appetite ;  which  inclination  regards,  first  of  all,  the  good, 
and  in  consequence,  the  rejection  of  a  contrary  evil.  Hence 
the  first  principle  of  this  appetitive  movement  is  love, 
which  is  the  first  inclination  of  the  appetite  towards  the 
possession  of  good:  while  the  second  principle  is  hatred, 
which  is  the  first  inchnation  of  the  appetite  towards  the 
avoidance  of  evil.  But  since  concupiscence  or  desire  is  the 
first  effect  of  love,  which  gives  rise  to  the  greatest  pleasure, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXH.,  A.  6) ;  hence  it  is  that  Augus- 
tine often  speaks  of  desire  or  concupiscence  in  the  sense  of 
love,  as  was  also  stated  (Q.  XXX.,  A.  2  ad  2):  and  in  this 
sense  he  says  that  desire  is  the  universal  cause  of  sorrow. 
Sometimes,  however,  desire  taken  in  its  proper  sense,  is  the 
cause  of  sorrow.  Because  whatever  hinders  a  movement 
from  reaching  its  end  is  contrary  to  that  movement.  Now 
that  which  is  contrary  to  the  movement  of  the  appetite, 
is  a  cause  of  sorrow.  Consequently,  desire  becomes  a  cause 
of  sorrow,  in  so  far  as  we  sorrow  for  the  delay  of  a  desired 


428  QUESTION  XXXVI 

good,  or  for  its  entire  removal.  But  it  cannot  be  a  universal 
cause  of  sorrow:  since  we  sorrow  more  for  the  loss  of 
present  good,  in  which  we  have  already  taken  pleasure,  than 
for  the  withdrawal  of  future  good  which  we  desire  to  have. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  inclination  of  the  appetite  to  the  pos- 
session of  good  causes  the  inclination  of  the  appetite  to  fly 
from  evil,  as  stated  above.  And  hence  it  is  that  the  appe- 
titive movements  that  regard  good,  are  reckoned  as  causing 
the  appetitive  movements  that  regard  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  That  which  is  desired,  though  really  future, 
is,  nevertheless,  in  a  way,  present,  inasmuch  as  it  is  hoped 
for. — Or  we  may  say  that  although  the  desired  good  itself  is 
future,  yet  the  hindrance  is  reckoned  as  present,  and  so 
gives  rise  to  sorrow. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Desire  gives  pleasure,  so  long  as  there  is  a 
hope  of  obtaining  that  which  is  desired.  But,  when  hope 
is  removed  through  the  presence  of  an  obstacle,  desire 
causes  sorrow. 

Third  Article, 
whether  the  craving  for  unity  is  a  cause  of  sorrow  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  the  craving  for  unity  is  not  a 
cause  of  sorrow.  For  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  x.)  that 
this  opinion,  which  held  repletion  to  be  the  cause  of  pleasure, 
and  division*  the  cause  of  sorrow,,  seems  to  have  originated 
in  pains  and  pleasures  connected  with  food.  But  not  every 
pleasure  or  sorrow  is  of  this  kind.  Therefore  the  craving 
for  unity  is  not  the  universal  cause  of  sorrow ;  since  repletion 
pertains  to  unity,  and  division  is  the  cause  of  multitude. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  every  separation  is  opposed  to  unity.  If 
therefore  sorrow  were  caused  by  a  craving  for  unity,  no 
separation  would  be  pleasant:  and  this  is  clearly  untrue  as 
regards  the  refusal  of  whatever  is  superfluous. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  for  the  same  reason  we  desire  the  con- 
junction of  good  and  the  removal  of  evil.     But  as  conjunc- 

*  Aristotle  wrote  evheiav ,  want ;  St .  Thomas  read  incisionem :  should 
he  have  read  indigentiam  ? 


OF  THE  CAUSES  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN        429 

tion  regards  unity,  since  it  is  a  kind  of  union ;  so  separation 
is  contrary  to  unity.  Therefore  the  craving  for  unity  should 
not  be  reckoned,  rather  than  the  craving  for  separation,  as 
causing  sorrow. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Lib.  Arh.  iii.),  that 
from  the  pain  that  dumb  animals  feel,  it  is  quite  evident  how 
their  souls  desire  unity,  in  ruling  and  quickening  their  bodies. 
For  what  else  is  pain  but  a  feeling  of  impatience  of  division 
or  corruption  ? 

I  answer  that.  Forasmuch  as  the  desire  or  craving  for  good 
is  reckoned  as  a  cause  of  sorrow,  so  must  a  craving  for  unity, 
and  love,  be  accounted  as  causing  sorrow.  Because  the 
good  of  each  thing  consists  in  a  certain  unity,  inasmuch  as 
each  thing  has,  united  in  itself,  the  elements  of  which  its 
perfection  consists:  wherefore  the  Platonists  held  that  one 
is  a  principle,  just  as  good  is.  Hence  everything  naturally 
desires  unity,  just  as  it  desires  goodness:  and  therefore,  just 
as  love  or  desire  for  good  is  a  cause  of  sorrow,  so  also  is  the 
love  or  craving  for  unity. 

Reply  Ob],  i.  Not  every  kind  of  union  causes  perfect  good- 
ness, but  only  that  on  which  the  perfect  being  of  a  thing 
depends.  Hence  neither  does  the  desire  of  any  kind  of 
unity  cause  pain  or  sorrow,  as  some  have  maintained :  whose 
opinion  is  refuted  by  the  Philosopher  from  the  fact  that 
repletion  is  not  always  pleasant;  for  instance,  when  a  man 
has  ate  to  repletion,  he  takes  no  further  pleasure  in  eating; 
because  repletion  or  union  of  this  kind,  is  repugnant  rather 
than  conducive  to  perfect  being.  Consequently  sorrow  is 
caused  by  the  craving,  not  for  any  kind  of  unity,  but  for 
that  unity  in  which  the  perfection  of  nature  consists. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Separation  can  be  pleasant,  either  because 
it  removes  something  contrary  to  a  thing's  perfection,  or 
because  it  has  some  union  connected  with  it,  such  as  union 
of  the  sense  to  its  object. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Separation  from  things  hurtful  and  corrup- 
tive is  desired,  in  so  far  as  they  destroy  the  unity  which  is 
due.  Wherefore  the  desire  for  a  suchlike  separation  is  not 
the  first  cause  of  sorrow,  whereas  the  craving  for  unity  is. 


430  QUESTION  XXXVI 


Fourth  Article, 
whether  an  irresistible  power  is  a  cause  of  sorrow  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  greater  power  should  not  be 
reckoned  a  cause  of  sorrow.  For  that  which  is  in  the  power 
of  the  agent  is  not  present  but  future.  But  sorrow  is  for 
present  evil.  Therefore  a  greater  power  is  not  a  cause  of 
sorrow. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  hurt  inflicted  is  the  cause  of  sorrow. 
But  hurt  can  be  inflicted  even  by  a  lesser  power.  Therefore 
a  greater  power  should  not  be  reckoned  as  a  cause  of  sorrow. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  interior  inclinations  of  the  soul  are 
the  causes  of  the  movements  of  appetite.  But  a  greater 
power  is  something  external.  Therefore  it  should  not  be 
reckoned  as  a  cause  of  sorrow. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {De  Nat.  Boni  xx.): 
Sorrow  in  the  soul  is  caused  by  the  will  resisting  a  stronger 
power  :  while  pain  in  the  body  is  caused  by  sense  resisting  a 
stronger  body. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  a  present  evil,  is 
cause  of  sorrow  or  pain,  by  way  of  object.  Therefore  that 
which  is  the  cause  of  the  evil  being  present,  should  be 
reckoned  as  causing  pain  or  sorrow.  Now  it  is  evident  that 
it  is  contrary  to  the  inclination  of  the  appetite  to  be  united 
with  a  present  evil:  and  whatever  is  contrary  to  a  thing's 
inclination  does  not  happen  to  it  save  by  the  action  of 
something  stronger.  Wherefore  Augustine  reckons  a  greater 
power  as  being  the  cause  of  sorrow. 

But  it  must  be  noted  that  if  the  stronger  power  goes  so 
far  as  to  transform  the  contrary  inclination  into  its  own 
inclination,  there  will  be  no  longer  repugnance  or  violence : 
thus  if  a  stronger  agent,  by  its  action  on  a  heavy  body, 
deprives  it  of  its  downward  tendency,  its  consequent 
upward  tendency  is  not  violent  but  natural  to  it. 

Accordingly  if  some  greater  power  prevail  so  far  as  to 
take  away  from  the  will  or  the  sensitive  appetite,  their 


OF  THE  CAUSES  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN       431 

respective  inclinations,  pain  or  sorrow  will  not  result  there- 
from ;  such  is  the  result  only  when  the  contrary  inclination 
of  the  appetite  remains.  And  hence  Augustine  says  that 
sorrow  is  caused  by  the  will  resisting  a  stronger  power  :  for 
were  it  not  to  resist,  but  to  yield  by  consenting,  the  result 
would  be  not  sorrow  but  pleasure. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  A  greater  power  causes  sorrow,  as  acting 
not  potentially  but  actually,  i.e.,  by  causing  the  actual 
presence  of  the  corruptive  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Nothing  hinders  a  power  which  is  not  simply 
greater,  from  being  greater  in  some  respect :  and  accordingly 
it  is  able  to  inflict  some  harm.  But  if  it  be  nowise  stronger, 
it  can  do  no  harm  at  all:  wherefore  it  cannot  bring  about 
that  which  causes  sorrow. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  External  agents  can  be  the  causes  of  appe- 
titive movements,  in  so  far  as  they  cause  the  presence  of 
the  object:  and  it  is  thus  that  a  greater  power  is  reckoned 
to  be  the  cause  of  sorrow. 


QUESTION  XXXVII. 

OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  effects  of  pain  or  sorrow:  under 
which  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether 
pain  deprives  one  of  the  power  to  learn  ?  (2)  Whether  the 
effect  of  sorrow  or  pain  is  to  burden  the  soul  ?  (3)  Whether 
sorrow  or  pain  weakens  all  activity  ?  (4)  Whether  sorrow 
is  more  harmful  to  the  body  than  all  the  other  passions  of 
the  soul  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  pain  deprives  one  of  the  power  to  learn  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  pain  does  not  deprive  one  of 
the  power  to  learn.  For  it  is  written  (Isa.  xxvi.  9):  When 
Thou  shalt  do  Thy  judgments  on  the  earth,  the  inhabitants  of 
the  world  shall  learn  justice  :  and  further  on  (verse  16) :  In 
the  tribulation  of  murmuring  Thy  instruction  was  with  them. 
But  the  judgments  of  God  and  tribulation  cause  sorrow  in 
men's  hearts.  Therefore  pain  or  sorrow,  far  from  destroy- 
ing, increases  the  power  of  learning. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  it  is  written  (Isa.  xxviii.  9):  Whom  shall 
He  teach  knowledge  ?  And  whom  shall  He  make  to  understand 
the  hearing  ?  Them  that  are  weaned  from  the  milk,  that  are 
drawn  away  from  the  breasts,  i.e.,  from  pleasures.  But  pain 
and  sorrow  are  most  destructive  of  pleasure;  since  sorrow 
hinders  all  pleasure,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  vii.:  and  (Ecclus. 
xi.  29)  it  is  stated  that  the  affliction  of  an  hour  maketh  one 
forget  great  delights.  Therefore  pain,  instead  of  taking  away, 
increases  the  faculty  of  learning. 

432 


•    OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW      433 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  inward  sorrow  surpasses  outward  pain, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXV.,  A.  7).  But  man  can  learn 
while  sorrowful.  Much  more,  therefore,  can  he  learn  while 
in  bodily  pain. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Soliloq.  i.):  Although 
during  those  days  I  was  tormented  with  a  violent  tooth-ache, — 
/  was  not  able  to  turn  over  in  my  mind  other  things  than  those 
I  had  already  learnt ;  and  as  to  learning  anything,  I  was 
quite  unequal  to  it,  because  it  required  undivided  attention. 

I  answer  that,  Since  all  the  powers  of  the  soul  are  rooted 
in  the  one  essence  of  the  soul,  it  must  needs  happen,  when 
the  intention  of  the  soul  is  strongly  drawn  towards  the 
action  of  one  power,  that  it  is  withdrawn  from  the  action  of 
another  power :  because  the  soul,  being  one,  can  only  have 
one  intention.  The  result  is  that  if  one  thing  draws  upon 
itself  the  entire  intention  of  the  soul,  or  a  great  portion 
thereof,  anything  else  requiring  considerable  attention  is 
incompatible  therewith. 

Now  it  is  evident  that  sensible  pain  above  all  draws  the 
soul's  intention  to  itself;  because  it  is  natural  for  each  thing 
to  tend  wholly  to  repel  whatever  is  contrary  to  it,  as  may 
be  observed  even  in  natural  things.  It  is  likewise  evident 
that  in  order  to  learn  anything  new,  we  require  study  and 
effort  with  a  strong  intention,  as  is  clearly  stated  in  Pro  v. 
ii.  4,  5 :  If  thou  shall  seek  wisdom  as  money,  and  shall  dig  for 
her  as  for  a  treasure,  then  shall  thou  understand  learning 
(Vulg., — the  fear  of  the  Lord).  Consequently  if  the  pain  be 
acute,  man  is  prevented  at  the  time  from  learning  anything : 
indeed  it  can  be  so  acute,  that,  as  long  as  it  lasts,  a  man  is 
unable  to  give  hi*s  attention  even  to  that  which  he  knew 
already. — ^However  a  difference  is  to  be  observed  according 
to  the  difference  of  love  that  a  man  has  for  learning  or  for 
considering :  because  the  greater  his  love,  the  more  will  he 
retain  the  intention  of  his  mind  so  as  to  prevent  it  from 
turning  entirely  to  the  pain. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Moderate  sorrow,  that  does  not  cause  the 
mind  to  wander,  can  conduce  to  the  acquisition  of  learning : 
especially  in  regard  to  those  things  by  which  a  man  hopes 

II.  I  28 


434  QUESTION  XXXVII 

to  be  freed  from  sorrow.     And  thus,  in  the  tribulation  of 
murmuring,  men  are  more  apt  to  be  taught  of  God. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Both  pleasure  and  pain,  in  so  far  as  they 
draw  upon  themselves  the  soul's  intention,  hinder  the  reason 
from  the  act  of  consideration,  wherefore  it  is  stated  in 
Ethic,  vii.  that  in  the  moment  of  sexual  pleasure,  a  man  cannot 
understand  anything.  Nevertheless  pain  attracts  the  soul's 
intention  more  than  pleasure  does:  thus  we  observe  in 
natural  things  that  the  action  of  a  natural  body  is  more 
intense  in  regard  to  its  contrary;  for  instance,  hot  water  is 
more  accessible  to  the  action  of  cold,  and  in  consequence 
freezes  harder.  If  therefore  pain  or  sorrow  be  moderate, 
it  can  conduce  accidentally  to  the  facility  of  learning,  in  so 
far  as  it  takes  away  an  excess  of  pleasure.  But,  of  itself,  it 
is  a  hindrance;  and  if  it  be  intense,  it  prevents  it  altogether. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  External  pain  arises  from  hurt  done  to  the 
body,  so  that  it  involves  bodily  transmutation  more  than 
inward  sorrow  does:  and  yet  the  latter  is  greater  in 
regard  to  the  formal  element  of  pain,  which  belongs  to 
the  soul.  Consequently  bodily  pain  is  a  greater  hindrance 
to  contemplation  which  requires  complete  repose,  than 
inward  sorrow  is.  Nevertheless  if  inward  sorrow  be  very 
intense,  it  attracts  the  intention,  so  that  man  is  unable  to 
learn  anything  for  the  first  time:  wherefore  on  account  of 
sorrow  Gregory  interrupted  his  commentary  on  Ezechiel 
{Hom.  xxii.  in  Ezechiel). 

Second  Article, 
whether  the  effect  of  sorrow  or  pain  is  to  burden 

THE   SOUL  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  it  is  not  an  effect  of  sorrow  to 
burden  the  soul.  For  the  Apostle  says  (2  Cor.  vii.  11): 
Behold  this  self-same  thing,  that  you  were  made  sorrowful 
according  to  God,  how  great  carefulness  it  worketh  in  you :  yea 
defence,  yea  indignation,  etc.  Now  carefulness  and  indigna- 
tion imply  that  the  soul  is  uplifted,  which  is  contrary  to 


OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW       435 

being  depressed.  Therefore  depression  is  not  an  effect  of 
sorrow. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  sorrow  is  contrary  to  pleasure.  But  the 
effect  of  pleasure  is  expansion :  the  opposite  of  which  is  not 
depression  but  contraction.  Therefore  depression  should 
not  be  reckoned  as  an  effect  of  sorrow. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  sorrow  consumes  those  who  are  afflicted 
therewith,  as  may  be  gathered  from  the  words  of  the  Apostle 
(2  Cor.  ii.  7):  Lest  perhaps  such  an  one  he  swallowed  up  with 
overmuch  sorrow.  But  that  which  is  depressed  is  not  con- 
sumed; nay,  it  is  weighed  down  by  something  heavy, 
whereas  that  which  is  consumed  enters  within  the  consumer. 
Therefore  depression  should  not  be  reckoned  an  effect  of 
sorrow. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius, — De  Nat. 
Horn,  xix.)  and  Damascene  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  speak  of 
depressing  sorrow. 

I  answer  that,  The  effects  of  the  soul's  passions  are  some- 
times named  metaphorically,  from  a  likeness  to  sensible 
bodies:  for  the  reason  that  the  movements  of  the  animal 
appetite  are  like  the  inclinations  of  the  natural  appetite.  And 
in  this  way  fervour  is  ascribed  to  love,  expansion  to  pleasure, 
and  depression  to  sorrow.  For  a  man  is  said  to  be  de- 
pressed, through  being  hindered  in  his  own  movement  by 
some  weight.  Now  it  is  evident  from  what  has  been  said 
above  (Q.  XXIII.,  A.  4;  Q.  XXV.,  A.  4;  Q.  XXXVL,  A.  i) 
that  sorrow  is  caused  by  a  present  evil:  and  this  evil,  from 
the  very  fact  that  it  is  repugnant  to  the  movement  of  the 
will,  depresses  the  soul,  inasmuch  as  it  hinders  it  from 
enjoying  that  which  it  wishes  to  enjoy.  And  if  the  evil 
which  is  the  cause  of  sorrow  be  not  so  strong  as  to  deprive 
one  of  the  hope  of  avoiding  it,  although  the  soul  be  de- 
pressed in  so  far  as,  for  the  present,  it  fails  to  grasp  that 
which  it  craves  for;  yet  it  retains  the  movement  whereby 
to  repulse  that  evil.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  the  strength  of 
the  evil  be  such  as  to  exclude  the  hope  of  evasion,  then  even 
the  interior  movement  of  the  afdicted  soul  is  absolutely 
hindered,  so  that  it  cannot  turn  aside  either  this  way  or 


436  QUESTION  XXXVII 

that.  Sometimes  even  the  external  movement  of  the  body 
is  paralyzed,  so  that  a  man  becomes  completely  stupefied. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  That  uplifting  of  the  soul  ensues  from  the 
sorrow  which  is  according  to  God,  because  it  brings  with  it 
the  hope  of  the  forgiveness  of  sin. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  As  far  as  the  movement  of  the  appetite  is 
concerned,  contraction  and  depression  amount  to  the  same : 
because  the  soul,  through  being  depressed  so  as  to  be  unable 
to  attend  freely  to  outward  things,  withdraws  to  itself, 
closing  itself  up  as  it  were. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Sorrow  is  said  to  consume  man,  when  the 
force  of  the  afflicting  evil  is  such  as  to  shut  out  all  hope  of 
evasion:  and  thus  also  it  both  depresses  and  consumes  at 
the  same  time.  For  certain  things,  taken  metaphorically, 
imply  one  another,  which  taken  literally,  appear  to  exclude 
one  another. 

Third  Article, 
whether  sorrow  or  pain  weakens  all  activity  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  sorrow  does  not  weaken  all 
activity.  Because  carefulness  is  caused  by  sorrow,  as  is 
clear  from  the  passage  of  the  Apostle  quoted  above  (A.  2, 
Ohj.  i).  But  carefulness  conduces  to  good  work:  wherefore 
the  Apostle  says  (2  Tim.  ii.  15):  Carefully  study  to  present 
thyself  ...  a  workman  that  needeth  not  to  he  ashamed. 
Therefore  sorrow  is  not  a  hindrance  to  work,  but  helps  one 
to  work  well. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  sorrow  causes  desire  in  many  cases,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  vii.  But  desire  causes  intensity  of  action. 
Therefore  sorrow  does  too. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  as  some  actions  are  proper  to  the  joyful, 
so  are  others  proper  to  the  sorrowful;  for  instance,  to 
mourn.  Now  a  thing  is  improved  by  that  which  is  suitable 
to  it.  Therefore  certain  actions  are  not  hindered  but 
improved  by  reason  of  sorrow. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  x. )  that  pleasure 
perfects  action,  whereas  on  the  other  hand,  sorrow  hinders  it. 


OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW      437 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  2),  Sorrow  at  times  does 
not  depress  or  consume  the  soul,  so  as  to  shut  out  all  move- 
ment, internal  or  external;  but  certain  movements  are  some- 
times caused  by  sorrow  itself.  Accordingly  action  stands 
in  a  twofold  relation  to  sorrow.  First,  as  being  the  object 
of  sorrow :  and  thus  sorrow  hinders  any  action :  for  we  never 
do  that  which  we  do  with  sorrow,  so  well  as  that  which  we 
do  with  pleasure,  or  without  sorrow.  The  reason  for  this  is 
that  the  will  is  the  cause  of  human  actions:  and  conse- 
quently when  we  do  something  that  gives  pain,  the  action 
must  of  necessity  be  weakened  in  consequence. — Secondly, 
action  stands  in  relation  to  sorrow,  as  to  its  principle  and 
cause :  and  such  action  must  needs  be  improved  by  sorrow : 
thus  the  more  one  sorrows  on  account  of  a  certain  thing, 
the  more  one  strives  to  shake  off  sorrow,  provided  there  is 
a  hope  of  shaking  it  off:  otherwise  no  movement  or  action 
would  result  from  that  sorrow. 

From  what  has  been  said  the  replies  to  the  objections  are 
evident. 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  sorrow  is  more  harmful  to  the  body  than 
the  other  passions  of  the  soul  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  sorrow  is  not  most  harmful 
to  the  body.  For  sorrow  has  a  spiritual  existence  in  the 
soul.  But  those  things  which  have  only  a  spiritual  existence 
do  not  cause  a  transmutation  in  the  body:  as  is  evident 
with  regard  to  the  images  of  colours,  which  images  are  in. 
the  air  and  do  not  give  colour  to  bodies.  Therefore  sorrow 
is  not  harmful  to  the  body. 

Ohj.  2.  Further  if  it  be  harmful  to  the  body,  this  can  only 
be  due  to  its  having  a  bodily  transmutation  in  conjunction 
with  it.  But  bodily  transmutation  takes  place  in  all  the 
passions  of  the  soul,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXII.,  AA.  i,  3). 
Therefore  sorrow  is  not  more  harmful  to  the  body  than  the 
other  passions  of  the  soul. 


438  QUESTION  XXXVII 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic.  vii.)that 
anger  and  desire  drive  some  to  madness  :  which  seems  to  be 
a  very  great  harm,  since  reason  is  the  most  excellent  thing 
in  man.  Moreover  despair  seems  to  be  more  harmful  than 
sorrow;  for  it  is  the  cause  of  sorrow.  Therefore  sorrow  is 
not  more  harmful  to  the  body  than  the  other  passions  of 
the  soul. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (Prov.  xvii.  22):  A  joyful 
mind  maketh  age  flourishing  :  a  sorrowful  spirit  drieth  up 
the  hones  :  and  (ihid.  xxv.  20):  As  a  moth  doth  hy  a  garment, 
and  a  worm  hy  the  wood  ;  so  the  sadness  of  a  man  consumeth 
the  heart :  and  (Ecclus.  xxxviii.  19) :  Of  sadness  cometh  death. 

I  answer  that,  Of  all  the  soul's  passions,  sorrow  is  most 
harmful  to  the  body.  The  reason  of  this  is  because  sorrow 
is  repugnant  to  man's  life  in  respect  of  the  species  of  its 
movement,  and  not  merely  in  respect  of  its  measure  or 
quantity,  as  is  the  case  with  the  other  passions  of  the  soul. 
For  man's  life  consists  in  a  certain  movement,  which  flows 
from  the  heart  to  the  other  parts  of  the  body:  and  this 
movement  is  befitting  to  human  nature  according  to  a  certain 
fixed  measure.  Consequently  if  this  movement  goes  beyond 
the  right  measure,  it  will  be  repugnant  to  man's  life  in 
respect  of  the  measure  of  quantity;  but  not  in  respect  of 
its  specific  character :  whereas  if  this  movement  be  hindered 
in  its  progress,  it  will  be  repugnant  to  life  in  respect  of  its 
species. 

Now  it  must  be  noted  that,  in  all  the  passions  of  the  soul, 
the  bodily  transmutation  which  is  their  material  element, 
is  in  conformity  with  and  in  proportion  to  the  appetitive 
movement,  which  is  the  formal  element:  just  as  in  every 
thing  matter  is  proportionate  to  form.  Consequently  those 
passions  that  imply  a  movement  of  the  appetite  in  pursuit 
of  something,  are  not  repugnant  to  the  vital  movement  as 
regards  its  species,  but  they  may  be  repugnant  thereto  as 
regards  its  measure:  such  are  love,  joy,  desire  and  the  like; 
wherefore  these  passions  conduce  to  the  well-being  of  the 
body;  though,  if  they  be  excessive,  they  may  be  harmful 
to  it. — On  the  other  hand,  those  passions  which  denote  in 


OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  PAIN  OR  SORROW       439 

the  appetite  a  movement  of  flight  or  contraction,  are  repug- 
nant to  the  vital  movement,  not  only  as  regards  its  measure, 
but  also  as  regards  its  species;  wherefore  they  are  simply 
harmful:  such  are  fear  and  despair,  and  above  all  sorrow, 
which  depresses  the  soul  by  reason  of  a  present  evil,  which 
makes  a  stronger  impression  than  future  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Since  the  soul  naturally  moves  the  body, 
the  spiritual  movement  of  the  soul  is  naturally  the  cause  of 
bodily  transmutation.  Nor  is  there  any  parallel  with 
spiritual  images,  because  they  are  not  naturally  ordained 
to  move  such  other  bodies  as  are  not  naturally  moved  by  the 
soul. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Other  passions  imply  a  bodily  transmuta- 
tion which  is  specifically  in  conformity  with  the  vital  move- 
ment: whereas  sorrow  implies  a  transmutation  that  is 
repugnant  thereto,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  A  lesser  cause  suffices  to  hinder  the  use  of 
reason,  than  to  destroy  life:  since  we  observe  that  many 
ailments  deprive  one  of  the  use  of  reason,  before  depriving 
one  of  life.  Nevertheless  fear  and  anger  cause  very  great 
harm  to  the  body,  by  reason  of  the  sorrow  which  they  imply, 
and  which  arises  from  the  absence  of  the  thing  desired. 
Moreover  sorrow  too  sometimes  deprives  man  of  the  use  of 
reason :  as  may  be  seen  in  those  who  through  sorrow  become 
a  prey  to  melancholy  or  madness. 


QUESTION  XXXVIII. 

OF  THE  REMEDIES  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN. 

{In  Five  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  remedies  of  pain  or  sorrow: 
under  which  head  there  are  five  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  pain  or  sorrow  is  assuaged  by  every  pleasure  ? 
(2)  Whether  it  is  assuaged  by  weeping  ?  (3)  Whether  it  is 
assuaged  by  the  sympathy  of  friends  ?  (4)  Whether  it  is 
assuaged  by  contemplating  the  truth  ?  {5)  Whether  it  is 
assuaged  by  sleep  and  baths  ? 

First  Article. 

whether  pain  or  sorrow  is  assuaged  by  every 

pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  not  every  pleasure  assuages 
every  pain  or  sorrow.  For  pleasure  does  not  assuage 
sorrow,  save  in  so  far  as  it  is  contrary  to  it:  for  remedies 
work  by  contraries  (Ethic,  ii.).  But  not  every  pleasure  is 
contrary  to  every  sorrow;  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXV., 
A.  4).     Therefore  not  every  pleasure  assuages  every  sorrow. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  that  which  causes  sorrow  does  not 
assuage  it.  But  some  pleasures  cause  sorrow;  since,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  ix.,  the  wicked  man  feels  pain  at  having  been 
pleased.     Therefore  not  every  pleasure  assuages  sorrow. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  [Conf.  iv.)  that  he  fled 
from  his  country,  where  he  had  been  wont  to  associate  with 
his  friend,  now  dead :  for  so  should  his  eyes  look  for  him  less, 
z&here  they  were  not  wont  to  see  him.     Hence  we  may  gather 

440 


OF  THE  REMEDIES  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN      441 

that  those  things  which  united  us  to  our  dead  or  absent 
friends,  become  burdensome  to  us  when  we  mourn  their 
death  or  absence.  But  nothing  united  us  more  than  the 
pleasures  we  enjoyed  in  common.  Therefore  these  very 
pleasures  become  burdensome  to  us  when  we  mourn. 
Therefore  not  every  pleasure  assuages  every  sorrow. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  vii.)  that 
sorrow  is  driven  forth  by  pleasure,  both  by  a  contrary  pleasure 
and  by  any  other,  provided  it  be  intense. 

I  answer  that,  As  is  evident  from  what  has  been  said  above 
(Q.  XXIII. ,  A.  4),  pleasure  is  a  kind  of  repose  of  the  appetite 
in  a  suitable  good;  while  sorrow  arises  from  something  un- 
suited  to  the  appetite.  Consequently  in  movements  of  the 
appetite  pleasure  is  to  sorrow,  what,  in  bodies,  repose  is  to 
weariness,  which  is  due  to  a  non-natural  transmutation;  for 
sorrow  itself  denotes  a  certain  weariness  or  ailing  of  the 
appetitive  faculty.  Therefore  just  as  all  repose  of  the  body 
brings  relief  to  any  kind  of  weariness,  ensuing  from  any 
non-natural  cause;  so  every  pleasure  brings  relief  by  assuag- 
ing any  kind  of  sorrow,  due  to  any  cause  whatever. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Although  not  every  pleasure  is  specifically 
contrary  to  every  sorrow,  yet  it  is  generically,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XXXV.,  A.  4).  And  consequently,  on  the  part 
of  the  disposition  of  the  subject,  any  sorrow  can  be  assuaged 
by  any  pleasure. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  pleasures  of  wicked  men  are  not  a 
cause  of  sorrow  while  they  are  enjoyed,  but  afterwards: 
that  is  to  say,  in  so  far  as  wicked  men  repent  of  those  things 
in  which  they  took  pleasure.  This  sorrow  is  healed  by 
contrary  pleasures. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  When  there  are  two  causes  inclining  to  con- 
trary movements,  each  hinders  the  other;  yet  the  one  which 
is  stronger  and  more  persistent,  prevails  in  the  end.  Now 
when  a  man  is  made  sorrowful  by  those  things  in  which  he 
took  pleasure  in  common  with  a  deceased  or  absent  friend, 
there  are  two  causes  producing  contrary  movements.  For 
the  thought  of  the  friend's  death  or  absence,  inclines  him 
to  sorrow:  whereas  the  present  good  inclines  him  to  pleasure. 


442  QUESTION  XXXVIII 

Consequently  each  is  modified  by  the  other.  And  yet,  since 
the  perception  of  the  present  moves  more  strongly  than  the 
memory  of  the  past,  and  since  love  of  self  is  more  per- 
sistent than  love  of  another;  hence  it  is  that,  in  the  end, 
the  pleasure  drives  out  the  sorrow.  Wherefore  a  little 
further  on  {loc.  cit.)  Augustine  says  that  his  sorrow  gave 
way  to  his  former  pleasures. 

Second  Article, 
whether  pain  or  sorrow  is  assuaged  by  tears  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  tears  do  not  assuage  sorrow. 
Because  no  effect  diminishes  its  cause.  But  tears  or  groans 
are  an  effect  of  sorrow.  Therefore  they  do  not  diminish 
sorrow. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  just  as  tears  or  groans  are  an  eifect  of 
sorrow,  so  laughter  is  an  effect  of  joy.  But  laughter  does 
not  lessen  joy.     Therefore  tears  do  not  lessen  sorrow. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  when  we  weep,  the  evil  that  saddens  us  is 
present  to  the  imagination.  But  the  image  of  that  which 
saddens  us  increases  sorrow,  just  as  the  image  of  a  pleasant 
thing  adds  to  joy.  Therefore  it  seems  that  tears  do  not 
assuage  sorrow. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [Conf.  iv.)  that  when  he 
mourned  the  death  of  his  friend,  in  groans  and  in  tears  alone 
did.  he  find  some  little  refreshment. 

I  answer  that,  Tears  and  groans  naturally  assuage  sorrow : 
and  this  for  two  reasons.  First,  because  a  hurtful  thing 
hurts  yet  more  if  we  keep  it  shut  up,  because  the  soul  is 
more  intent  on  it:  whereas  if  it  be  allowed  to  escape,  the 
soul's  intention  is  dispersed  as  it  were  on  outward  things, 
so  that  the  inward  sorrow  is  lessened.  This  is  why  when 
men,  burdened  with  sorrow,  make  outward  show  of  their 
sorrow,  by  tears  or  groans  or  even  by  words,  their  sorrow  is 
assuaged. — Secondly,  because  an  action,  that  befits  a  man 
according  to  his  actual  disposition,  is  always  pleasant  to 
him.     Now  tears  and  groans  are  actions  befitting  a  man 


OF  THE  REMEDIES  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN     443 

who  is  in  sorrow  or  pain;  and  consequently  they  become 
pleasant  to  him.  Since  then,  as  stated  above  (A.  i),  every 
pleasure  assuages  sorrow  or  pain  somewhat,  it  follows  that 
sorrow  is  assuaged  by  plaints  and  groans. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  very  relation  of  cause  to  effect  is  con- 
trary to  the  relation  between  the  sorrowing  man  and  his 
sorrow :  because  every  effect  agrees  with  its  cause,  and  con- 
sequently is  pleasant  to  it;  whereas  the  cause  of  sorrow  is 
disagreeable  to  him  that  sorrows.  Consequently  the  rela- 
tion of  the  cause  of  sorrow  to  the  sorrowful  is  contrary 
to  the  relation  of  sorrow  to  its  cause;  so  that  sorrow  is 
assuaged  by  its  effect,  on  account  of  the  aforesaid  con- 
trariety. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  relation  of  effect  to  cause  is  like  the 
relation  of  the  object  of  pleasure  to  him  that  takes  pleasure 
in  it:  because  in  each  case  the  one  agrees  with  the  other. 
Now  every  like  thing  increases  its  like.  Therefore  joy  is 
increased  by  laughter  and  the  other  effects  of  joy :  except 
they  be  excessive,  in  which  case,  accidentally,  they  lessen  it. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  image  of  that  which  saddens  us,  con- 
sidered in  itself,  has  a  natural  tendency  to  increase  sorrow: 
yet  from  the  very  fact  that  a  man  imagines  himself  to  be 
doing  that  which  is  fitting  according  to  his  actual  state,  he 
feels  a  certain  amount  of  pleasure.  For  the  same  reason 
if  laughter  escapes  a  man  when  he  is  so  disposed  that  he 
thinks  he  ought  to  weep,  he  is  sorry  for  it,  as  having  done 
something  unbecoming  to  him,  as  Tully  says  {Tusc.  Quaest. 

iii.). 

Third  Article. 

whether  pain  and  sorrow  are  assuaged  by  the 
sympathy  of  friends  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  sorrow  of  sympathizing 
friends  does  not  assuage  our  own  sorrow.  For  contraries 
have  contrary  effects.  Now  as  Augustine  says  (Conf.  viii.), 
when  many  rejoice  together,  each  one  has  more  exuberant  joy, 
for  they  are  kindled  and  inflamed  one  hy  the  other.     Therefore, 


444  QUESTION  XXXVIII 

in  like  manner,  when  many  are  sorrowful,  it  seems  that 
their  sorrow  is  greater. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  friendship  demands  mutual  love,  as 
Augustine  declares  {Conf.  iv.).  But  a  sympathizing  friend 
is  pained  at  the  sorrow  of  his  friend  with  whom  he  sym- 
pathizes. Consequently  the  pain  of  a  sympathizing  friend 
becomes,  to  the  friend  in  sorrow,  a  further  cause  of  sorrow : 
so  that  his  pain,  being  doubled,  his  sorrow  seems  to  in- 
crease. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  sorrow  arises  from  every  evil  affecting  a 
friend,  as  though  it  affected  oneself:  since  a  friend  is  ones 
other  self  {Ethic,  ix.).  But  sorrow  is  an  evil.  Therefore  the 
sorrow  of  the  sympathizing  friend  increases  the  sorrow  of  the 
friend  with  whom  he  sympathizes. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  ix.)  that 
those  who  are  in  pain  are  consoled  when  their  friends  sym- 
pathize with  them. 

I  answer  that,  When  one  is  in  pain,  it  is  natmral  that  the 
sympathy  of  a  friend  should  afford  consolation :  whereof  the 
Philosopher  indicates  a  twofold  reason  {Ethic,  ix.).  The 
first  is  because,  since  sorrow  has  a  depressing  effect,  it  is 
like  a  weight  whereof  we  strive  to  unburden  ourselves:  so 
that  when  a  man  sees  others  saddened  by  his  own  sorrow, 
it  seems  as  though  others  were  bearing  the  burden  with 
him,  striving,  as  it  were,  to  lessen  its  weight ;  w^herefore  the 
load  of  sorrow  becomes  lighter  for  him:  something  like  this 
occurs  in  the  carrying  of  bodily  burdens. — The  second  and 
better  reason  is  because  when  a  man's  friends  condole  with 
him,  he  sees  that  he  is  loved  by  them,  and  this  affords  him 
pleasure,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXII.,  A.  5).  Consequently, 
since  every  pleasure  assuages  sorrow,  as  stated  above 
(A.  i),  it  follows  that  sorrow  is  mitigated  by  a  sympathizing 
friend. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  In  either  case  there  is  a  proof  of  friendship, 
viz.,  when  a  man  rejoices  with  the  joyful,  and  w^hen  he 
sorrows  with  the  sorrowful.  Consequently  each  becomes  an 
object  of  pleasure  by  reason  of  its  cause. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  friend's  sorrow  itself  would  be  a  cause 


OF  THE  REMEDIES  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN     445 

of  sorrow:  but  consideration  of    its  cause,  viz.,  his  love, 
gives  rise  rather  to  pleasure. 

And  this  suffices  for  the  reply  to  the  Third  Objection. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  pain  and  sorrow  are  assuaged  by  the  con- 
templation of  truth  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  the  contemplation  of  truth  does 
not  assuage  sorrow.  For  it  is  written  (Eccles.  i.  18) :  He 
that  addeth  knowledge  addeth  also  sorrow  (Vulg., — labour). 
But  knowledge  pertains  to  the  contemplation  of  truth. 
Therefore  the  contemplation  of  truth  does  not  assuage  sorrow. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  contemplation  of  truth  belongs  to  the 
speculative  intellect.  But  the  speculative  intellect  is  not  a 
principle  of  movement ;  as  stated  in  De  Anima  iii.  There- 
fore, since  joy  and  sorrow  are  movements  of  the  soul,  it 
seems  that  the  contemplation  of  truth  does  not  help  to 
assuage  sorrow. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  remedy  for  an  ailment  should  be 
applied  to  the  part  which  ails.  But  contemplation  of  truth 
is  in  the  intellect.  Therefore  it  does  not  assuage  bodily 
pain  which  is  in  the  senses. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Soliloq.  i.) :  It  seemed  to 
me  that  if  the  light  of  that  truth  were  to  dawn  on  our  minds, 
either  I  should  not  feel  that  pain,  or  at  least  that  the  pain 
would  seem  nothing  to  me. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  III.,  A.  5),  the  greatest 
of  all  pleasures  consists  in  the  contemplation  of  truth. 
Now  every  pleasure  assuages  pain  as  stated  above  (A.  i) : 
hence  the  contemplation  of  truth  assuages  pain  or  sorrow, 
and  the  more  so,  the  more  perfectly  one  is  a  lover  of  wisdom. 
And  therefore  in  the  midst  of  tribulations  men  rejoice  in  the 
contemplation  of  Divine  things  and  of  future  Happiness, 
according  to  James  i.  2:  My  brethren,  count  it  all  joy,  when 
you  shall  fall  into  divers  temptations  :  and,  what  is  more,  even 
in  the  midst  (jf  bodily  tortures  this  joy  is  found;  as  the  martyr 


446  QUESTION  XXXVIII 

TiHirtiuSi  ivhen  he  was  walking  barefoot  on  the  burning  coals, 
said :  Methinks,  I  walk  on  roses,  in  the  name  of  Jesus  Christ. 
(Cf.  Dominican  Breviary,  August  lo,  commemoration  of 
S.  Tiburtius.) 

Reply  Obj.  i.  He  that  addeth  knowledge,  addeth  sorrow, 
either  on  account  of  the  difficulty  and  disappointment  in 
the  search  of  truth;  or  because  knowledge  makes  man  ac- 
quainted with  many  things  that  are  contrary  to  his  will. 
Accordingly,  on  the  part  of  the  things  known,  knowledge 
causes  sorrow:  but  on  the  part  of  the  contemplation  of 
truth,  it  causes  pleasure. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  speculative  intellect  does  not  move  the 
mind  on  the  part  of  the  thing  contemplated :  but  on  the  part 
of  contemplation  itself,  which  is  man's  good  and  naturally 
pleasant  to  him. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  the  powers  of  the  soul  there  is  an  over- 
flow from  the  higher  to  the  lower  powers :  and  accordingly,  the 
pleasure  of  contemplation,  which  is  in  the  higher  part,  over- 
flows so  as  to  mitigate  even  that  pain  which  is  in  the  senses. 

Fifth  Article. 

whether  pain  and  sorrow  are  assuaged  by  sleep 

and  baths  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  sleep  and  baths  do  not  assuage 
sorrow.  For  sorrow  is  in  the  soul :  whereas  sleep  and  baths 
regard  the  body.  Therefore  they  do  not  conduce  to  the 
assuaging  of  sorrow. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  same  effect  does  not  seem  to  ensue 
from  contrary  causes.  But  these,  being  bodily  things,  are 
incompatible  with  the  contemplation  of  truth,  which  is  a 
cause  of  the  assuaging  of  sorrow,  as  stated  above  (A.  4). 
Therefore  sorrow  is  not  mitigated  by  the  like. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Sorrow  and  pain,  in  so  far  as  they  affect 
the  body,  denote  a  certain  transmutation  of  the  heart. 
But  such  remedies  as  these  seem  to  pertain  to  the  outward 
senses  and  limbs,  rather  than  to  the  interior  disposition  of 
the  heart.     Therefore  they  do  not  assuage  pain. 


OF  THE  REMEDIES  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN     447 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  [Conf.  ix.) :  I  had  heard 
that  the  hath  had  its  name*  .  .  .  from  the  fact  of  its  driving 
sadness  from  the  mind.  And  further  on,  he  says:  /  slept, 
and  woke  up  again,  and  found  my  grief  not  a  little  assuaged  : 
and  quotes  the  words  from  the  hymn  of  Ambrose  (cf. 
Sarum  Breviary:  First  Sunday  after  the  octave  of  the 
Epiphany,  H^^mn  for  first  Vespers),  in  which  it  is  said  that 
Sleep  restores  the  tired  limbs  to  labour,  refreshes  the  weary 
mind,  and  banishes  sorrow. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXXVII.,  A.  4), 
Sorrow,  by  reason  of  its  specific  nature,  is  repugnant  to  the 
vital  movement  of  the  body;  and  consequently  whatever 
restores  the  bodily  nature  to  its  due  state  of  vital  movement, 
is  opposed  to  sorrow  and  assuages  it. — Moreover  such 
remedies,  from  the  very  fact  that  they  bring  nature  back 
to  its  normal  state,  are  causes  of  pleasure;  for  this  is  pre- 
cisely in  what  pleasure  consists,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXI., 
A.  i).  Therefore,  since  every  pleasure  assuages  sorrow, 
sorrow  is  assuaged  by  suchlike  bodily  remedies. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  normal  disposition  of  the  body,  so  far 
as  it  is  felt,  is  itself  a  cause  of  pleasure,  and  consequently 
assuages  sorrow. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXXI.,  A.  8),  one 
pleasure  hinders  another;  and  yet  every  pleasure  assuages 
sorrow.  Consequently  it  is  not  unreasonable  that  sorrow 
should  be  assuaged  by  causes  which  hinder  one  another. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Every  good  disposition  of  the  body  reacts 
somewhat  on  the  heart,  which  is  the  beginning  and  end  of 
bodily  movements,  as  stated  in  De  Causa  Mot.  Animal,  xi. 

*  Balneum,  from  the  Greek  ^aXavelov. 


QUESTION  XXXIX. 

OF  THE  GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  goodness  and  malice  of  pain 
or  sorrow:  under  which  head  there  are  four  points  of  in- 
quiry :  (i)  Whether  all  sorrow  is  evil  ?  (2)  Whether  sorrow 
can  be  a  virtuous  good  ?  (3)  Whether  it  can  be  a  useful 
good  ?     (4)  Whether  bodily  pain  is  the  greatest  evil  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  all  sorrow  is  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — • 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  all  sorrow  is  evil.  For  Gregory 
of  Nyssa  {Nemesius,  De  Nat.,  Horn,  xix.)  says:  All  sorrow 
is  evil,  from  its  very  nature.  Now  what  is  naturally  evil,  is 
evil  always  and  everywhere.     Therefore  all  sorrow  is  evil. 

Ohj,  2.  Further,  That  which  all,  even  the  virtuous,  avoid, 
is  evil.  But  all  avoid  sorrow,  even  the  virtuous,  since  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  vii.,  though  the  prudent  man  does  not  aim 
at  pleasure,  yet  he  aims  at  avoiding  sorrow.  Therefore  sorrow 
is  evil. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Just  as  bodily  evil  is  the  object  and  cause 
of  bodily  pain,  so  spiritual  evil  is  the  object  and  cause  of 
sorrow  in  the  soul.  But  every  bodily  pain  is  a  bodily  evil. 
Therefore  every  sorrow  of  the  soul  is  an  evil  of  the  soul. 

On  the  contrary,  Sorrow  for  evil  is  contrary  to  pleasure  in 
evil.  But  pleasure  in  evil  is  evil ;  wherefore,  in  condemnation 
of  certain  men,  it  is  written  (Pro v.  ii.  14),  that  they  are  glad 
when  they  have  done  evil.    Therefore  sorrow  for  evil  is  good. 

448 


GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN    449 

/  answer  that,  A  thing  may  be  good  or  evil  in  two  ways: 
first  considered  simply  and  in  itself;  and  thus  all  sorrow 
is  an  evil,  because  the  mere  fact  of  a  man's  appetite  being 
uneasy  about  a  present  evil,  is  itself  an  evil,  because  it 
hinders  the  repose  of  the  appetite  in  good. — Secondly,  a 
thing  is  said  to  be  good  or  evil,  on  the  supposition  of  some- 
thing else :  thus  shame  is  said  to  be  good,  on  the  supposition 
of  a  shameful  deed  done,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iv.  Accord- 
ingly, supposing  the  presence  of  something  saddening  or 
painful,  it  is  a  sign  of  goodness  if  a  man  is  in  sorrow  or  pain 
on  account  of  this  present  evil.  For  if  he  were  not  to  be 
in  sorrow  or  pain,  this  could  only  be  either  because  he 
feels  it  not,  or  because  he  does  not  reckon  it  as  something 
unbecoming,  both  of  which  are  manifest  evils.  Conse- 
quently it  is  a  condition  of  goodness,  that,  supposing  an 
evil  to  be  present,  sorrow  or  pain  should  ensue.  Wherefore 
Augustine  says  [Gen.  ad  lit.  viii.) :  It  is  also  a  good  thing 
that  he  sorrows  for  the  good  he  has  lost :  for  had  not  some  good 
remained  in  his  nature,  he  could  not  he  punished  hy  the  loss 
of  good. — Because,  however,  in  the  science  of  Morals,  we 
consider  things  individually, — for  actions  are  concerned 
about  individuals, — that  which  is  good  hypothetically, 
should  be  considered  as  good:  just  as  that  which  is  volun- 
tary, on  some  supposition,  is  judged  to  be  voluntary,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  iii.,  and  likewise  above  (Q.  VI.,  A.  6). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Gregory  of  Nyssa  is  speaking  of  sorrow  on 
the  part  of  the  evil  that  causes  it,  but  not  on  the  part  of 
the  subject  that  feels  and  rejects  the  evil. — And  from  this 
point  of  view  all  shun  sorrow,  inasmuch  as  they  shun  evil: 
but  they  do  not  shun  the  perception  and  rejection  of  evil. — ■ 
The  same  also  applies  to  bodily  pain :  because  the  perception 
and  rejection  of  bodily  evil  is  the  proof  of  the  goodness  of 
nature. 

This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Second  and  Third 
Objections. 


II.  I  29 


450  QUESTION  XXXIX 


Second  Article, 
whether  sorrow  can  be  a  virtuous  good  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 
Objection  i.  It  seems  that  sorrow  is  not  a  virtuous  good. 
For  that  which  leads  to  hell  is  not  a  virtuous  good.  But, 
as  Augustine  says  [Gen.  ad  lit.  xii.),  Jacob  seems  to  have 
feared  lest  he  should  be  troubled  overmuch  by  sorrow,  and  so, 
instead  of  entering  into  the  rest  of  the  blessed,  be  consigned 
to  the  hell  of  sinners.  Therefore  sorrow  is  not  a  virtuous 
good. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  virtuous  good  is  praiseworthy  and 
meritorious.  But  sorrow  lessens  praise  or  merit:  for  the 
Apostle  says  (2  Cor.  ix.  7) :  Everyone,  as  he  hath  determined 
in  his  heart,  not  with  sadness,  or  of  necessity.  Therefore 
sorrow  is  not  a  virtuous  good. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  As  Augustine  says  [De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.), 
sorrow  is  concerned  about  those  things  which  happen  against 
our  will.  But  not  to  will  those  things  which  are  actually 
taking  place,  is  to  have  a  will  opposed  to  the  decree  of  God, 
to  Whose  providence  whatever  is  done  is  subject.  Since, 
then,  conformity  of  the  human  to  the  Divine  will  is  a  con- 
dition of  the  rectitude  of  the  will,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XIX., 
A.  9),  it  seems  that  sorrow  is  incompatible  with  rectitude 
of  the  will,  and  that  consequently  it  is  not  virtuous. 

On  the  contrary,  Whatever  merits  the  reward  of  eternal 
life  is  virtuous.  But  such  is  sorrow;  as  is  evident  from 
Matth.  V.  5:  Blessed  are  they  that  mourn,  for  they  shall  be 
comforted.     Therefore  sorrow  is  a  virtuous  good. 

/  answer  that,  In  so  far  as  sorrow  is  good,  it  can  be  a 
virtuous  good.  For  it  has  been  said  above  (A.  i)  that  sorrow 
is  a  good  inasmuch  as  it  denotes  perception  and  rejection  of 
evil.  These  two  things,  as  regards  bodily  pain,  are  a  proof 
of  the  goodness  of  nature,  to  which  it  is  due  that  the  senses 
perceive,  and  that  nature  shuns,  the  harmful  thing  that 
causes  pain.  As  regards  interior  sorrow,  perception  of  the 
evil  is  sometimes  due  to  a  right  judgment  of  reason;  while 


GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN    451 

the  rejection  of  the  evil  is  the  act  of  the  will,  well  disposed 
and  detesting  that  evil.  Now  every  virtuous  good  results 
from  these  two  things,  the  rectitude  of  the  reason  and  of  the 
will.  Wherefore  it  is  evident  that  sorrow  may  be  a  virtuous 
good. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  All  the  passions  of  the  soul  should  be  regu- 
lated according  to  the  rule  of  reason,  which  is  the  root  of 
the  virtuous  good :  but  excessive  sorrow,  of  which  Augustine 
is  speaking,  oversteps  this  rule,  and  therefore  it  fails  to  be  a 
virtuous  good. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Just  as  sorrow  for  an  evil  arises  from  a 
right  will  and  reason,  which  detest  the  evil,  so  sorrow  for  a 
good  is  due  to  a  perverse  reason  and  will,  which  detest  the 
good.  Consequently  such  sorrow  is  an  obstacle  to  the 
praise  and  merit  of  the  virtuous  good;  for  instance,  when  a 
man  gives  an  alms  sorrowfully. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Some  things  do  actually  happen,  not  be- 
cause God  wills,  but  because  He  permits  them  to  happen, — 
such  as  sins.  Consequently  a  will  that  is  opposed  to  sin, 
whether  in  oneself  or  in  another,  is  not  discordant  from  the 
Divine  will. — Penal  evils  happen  actually,  even  by  God's 
will.  But  it  is  not  necessary  for  the  rectitude  of  his  will, 
that  man  should  will  them  in  themselves:  but  only  that  he 
should  not  revolt  against  the  order  of  Divine  justice,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  XIX.,  A.  10). 

Third  Article, 
whether  sorrow  can  be  a  useful  good  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  sorrow  cannot  be  a  useful  good. 
For  it  is  written  (Ecchis.  xxx.  25) :  Sadness  hath  killed 
many,  and  there  is  no  profit  in  it. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  choice  is  of  that  which  is  useful  to  an  end. 
But  sorrow  is  not  an  object  of  choice ;  in  fact,  a  thing  without 
sorrow  is  to  be  chosen  rather  than  the  same  thing  with  sorrow 
{Topic,  iii.).     Therefore  sorrow  is  not  a  useful  good. 

Obj.   3.  Further,   Everything  is   for  the  sake  of  its  own 


452  QUESTION  XXXIX 

operation,  as  stated  in  De  Ccelo  ii.  But  sorrow  hinders  opera- 
tion, as  stated  in  Ethic,  x.  Therefore  sorrow  is  not  a  useful 
good. 

On  the  contrary.  The  wise  man  seeks  only  that  which  is 
useful.  But  according  to  Eccles.  vii.,  the  heart  of  the  wise 
is  where  there  is  monrning,  and  the  heart  of  fools  where  there 
is  mirth.     Therefore  sorrow  is  useful. 

/  answer  that,  A  twofold  movement  of  the  appetite  ensues 
from  a  present  evil.  One  is  that  whereby  the  appetite  is 
opposed  to  the  present  evil;  and,  in  this  respect,  sorrow  is 
of  no  use;  because  that  which  is  present,  cannot  be  not 
present. — The  other  movement  arises  in  the  appetite  to  the 
effect  of  avoiding  or  expelling  the  saddening  evil:  and,  in 
this  respect,  sorrow  is  of  use,  if  it  be  for  something  which 
ought  to  be  avoided.  Because  there  are  two  reasons  for 
which  it  may  be  right  to  avoid  a  thing.  First,  because  it 
should  be  avoided  in  itself,  on  account  of  its  being  contrary 
to  good;  for  instance,  sin.  Wherefore  sorrow  for  sin  is 
useful  as  inducing  man  to  avoid  sin:  hence  the  Apostle 
says  (2  Cor.  vii.  9) :  /  am  glad :  not  because  you  iiuere  made 
sorrowful,  hut  because  you  were  made  sorrowful  unto  penance. 
— Secondly,  a  thing  is  to  be  avoided,  not  as  though  it  were 
evil  in  itself,  but  because  it  is  an  occasion  of  evil;  either 
through  one's  being  attached  to  it,  and  loving  it  too  much, 
or  through  one's  being  thrown  headlong  thereby  into  an 
evil,  as  is  evident  in  the  case  of  temporal  goods.  And,  in  this 
respect,  sorrow  for  temporal  goods  may  be  useful;  according 
to  Eccles.  vii.  3:  It  is  better  to  go  to  the  house  of  mourning, 
than  to  the  house  of  feasting  :  for  in  that  we  are  put  in  mind 
of  the  end  of  all.  * 

Moreover,  sorrow  for  that  which  ought  to  be  avoided  is 
always  useful,  since  it  adds  another  motive  for  avoiding  it. 
Because  the  very  evil  is  in  itself  a  thing  to  be  avoided: 
while  everyone  avoids  sorrow  for  its  own  sake,  just  as  every- 
one seeks  the  good,  and  pleasure  in  the  good.  Therefore 
just  as  pleasure  in  the  good  makes  one  seek  the  good  more 
earnestly,  so  sorrow  for  evil  makes  one  avoid  evil  more 
eagerly. 


GOODNESS  AND  MALICE  OF  SORROW  OR  PAIN    453 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  passage  is  to  be  taken  as  referring  to 
excessive  sorrow,  which  consumes  the  soul:  for  such  sorrow 
paralyzes  the  soul,  and  hinders  it  from  shunning  evil,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  XXXVII.,  A.  2). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Just  as  any  object  of  choice  becomes  less 
eligible  by  reason  of  sorrow,  so  that  which  ought  to  be 
shunned  is  still  more  to  be  shunned  by  reason  of  sorrow: 
and,  in  this  respect,  sorrow  is  useful. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Sorrow  caused  by  an  action  hinders  that 
action :  but  sorrow  for  the  cessation  of  an  action,  makes  one 
do  it  more  earnestly. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  bodily  pain  is  the  greatest  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  pain  is  the  greatest  evil.  Be- 
cause the  worst  is  contrary  to  the  best  (Ethic,  viii.).  But  a 
certain  pleasure  is  the  greatest  good,  viz.,  the  pleasure  of 
bliss.     Therefore  a  certain  pain  is  the  greatest  evil. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Happiness  is  man's  greatest  good,  because 
it  is  his  last  end.  But  man's  Happiness  consists  in  his 
having  whatever  he  will,  and  in  willing  naught  amiss,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  III.,  A.  4,  Ohj.  5;  Q.  V.,  A.  8,  Obj.  3).  Therefore 
man's  greatest  good  consists  in  the  fulfilment  of  his  will. 
Now  pain  consists  in  something  happening  contrary  to  the 
will,  as  Augustine  declares  (De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.).  Therefore 
pain  is  man's  greatest  evil. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  argues  thus  (Soliloq.  i.) :  We 
are  composed  of  two  parts,  i.e.  of  a  sottl  and  a  body,  whereof 
the  body  is  the  inferior.  Noin)  the  sovereign  good  is  the  greatest 
good  of  the  better  part :  while  the  supreme  evil  is  the  greatest 
evil  of  the  inferior  part.  But  wisdom  is  the  greatest  good  of 
the  soul  ;  while  the  worst  thing  in  the  body  is  pain.  Therefore 
man's  greatest  good  is  to  be  wise  :  while  his  greatest  evil  is  to 
suffer  patn. 

On  the  contrary,  Guilt  is  a  greater  evil  than  pimishment 
as  was  stated  in  the  First  Part  (Q.  XLVIIL,  A.  6).     But, 


454  QUESTION  XXXIX 

sorrow  or  pain  belongs  to  the  punishment  of  sin,  just  as  the 
enjoyment  of  changeable  things  is  an  evil  of  guilt.  For 
Augustine  says  {De  Vera  Relig.  xii.) :  What  is  fain  of  the 
soul,  except  for  the  soul  to  he  deprived  of  that  which  it  was 
wont  to  enjoy,  or  had  hoped  to  enjoy  ?  And  this  is  all  that 
is  called  evil,  i.e.  sin,  and  the  punishment  of  sin.  Therefore 
sorrow  or  pain  is  not  man's  greatest  evil. 

I  answer  that.  It  is  impossible  for  any  sorrow  or  pain  to 
be  man's  greatest  evil.  For  all  sorrow  or  pain  is  either 
for  something  that  is  truly  evil,  or  for  something  that  is 
apparently  evil,  but  good  in  reality.  Now  pain  or  sorrow 
for  that  which  is  truly  evil  cannot  be  the  greatest  evil:  for 
there  is  something  worse,  namely,  either  not  to  reckon  as 
evil  that  which  is  really  evil,  or  not  to  reject  it.  Again, 
sorrow  or  pain,  for  that  which  is  apparently  evil,  but  really 
good,  cannot  be  the  greatest  evil,  for  it  would  be  worse  to 
be  altogether  separated  from  that  which  is  truly  good. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Pleasure  and  sorrow  have  two  good  points 
in  common:  namely,  a  true  judgment  concerning  good  and 
evil;  and  the  right  order  of  the  will  in  approving  of  good 
and  rejecting  evil.  Thus  it  is  clear  that  in  pain  or  sorrow 
there  is  a  good,  by  the  removal  of  which  they  become 
worse :  and  yet  there  is  not  an  evil  in  every  pleasure,  by  the 
removal  of  which  the  pleasure  is  better.  Consequently,  a 
pleasure  can  be  man's  highest  good,  in  the  way  above  stated 
(Q.  XXXIV.,  A.  3):  whereas  sorrow  cannot  be  man's 
greatest  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  very  fact  of  the  will  being  opposed  to 
evil  is  a  good.  And  for  this  reason,  sorrow  or  pain  cannot 
be  the  greatest  evil;  because  it  has  an  admixture  of  good. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  That  which  harms  the  better  thing  is  worse 
than  that  which  harms  the  worse.  Now  a  thing  is  called 
evil  hecauseit  harms,  as  Augustine  says  {Enchirid.  xii.).  There- 
fore that  which  is  an  evil  to  the  soul  is  a  greater  evil  than 
that  which  is  an  evil  to  the  body.  Therefore  this  argument 
does  not  prove:  nor  does  Augustine  give  it  as  his  own,  but 
as  taken  from  another.* 

*  Cornelius  Celsus. 


QUESTION  XL. 

OF  THE  IRASCIBLE  PASSIONS,  AND  FIRST,  OF 
HOPE  AND  DESPAIR. 

[In  Eight  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  irascible  passions;  (i)  Hope 
and  despair;  (2)  Fear  and  daring;  (3)  Anger.  Under  the 
first  head  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether 
hope  is  the  same  as  desire  or  cupidity  ?  (2)  Whether  hope 
is  in  the  apprehensive,  or  in  the  appetitive  faculty  ? 
(3)  Whether  hope  is  in  dumb  animals  ?  (4)  Whether  despair 
is  contrary  to  hope  ?  (5)  Whether  experience  is  a  cause  of 
hope  ?  (6)  Whether  hope  abounds  in  young  men  and 
drunkards  ?  (7)  Concerning  the  order  of  hope  to  love  ? 
(8)  Whether  hope  conduces  to  action  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  hope  is  the  same  as  desire  or  cupidity  ? 

We  -proceed  thus  to  the  First  A  rticle  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  hope  is  the  same  as  desire  or 
cupidity.  Because  hope  is  reckoned  as  one  of  the  four  • 
principal  passions.  But  Augustine  in  setting  down  the 
four  principal  passions  puts  cupidity  in  the  place  of  hope 
{De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.).  Therefore  hope  is  the  same  as  cupidity 
or  desire. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Passions  differ  according  to  their  objects. 
But  the  object  of  hope  is  the  same  as  the  object  of  cupidity 
or  desire,  viz.,  the  future  good.  Therefore  hope  is  the  same 
as  cupidity  or  desire. 

Obj.  3.  If  it  be  said  that  hope,  in  addition  to  desire,  denotes 

455 


456  QUESTION  XL 

the  possibility  of  obtaining  the  future  good;  on  the  contrary, 
whatever  is  accidental  to  the  object  does  not  make  a  dif- 
ferent species  of  passions.  But  possibility  of  acquisition  is 
accidental  to  a  future  good,  which  is  the  object  of  cupidity 
or  desire,  and  of  hope.  Therefore  hope  does  not  differ 
specifically  from  desire  or  cupidity. 

On  the  contrary,  To  different  powers  belong  different  species 
of  passions.  But  hope  is  in  the  irascible  power;  whereas 
desire  or  cupidity  is  in  the  concupiscible.  Therefore  hope- 
differs  specifically  from  desire  or  cupidity. 

/  answer  that,  The  species  of  a  passion  is  taken  from  the 
object.  Now,  in  the  object  of  hope,  we  may  note  four  con- 
ditions. First,  that  it  is  something  good;  since,-  properly 
speaking,  hope  regards  only  the  good;  in  this  respect,  hope 
differs  from  fear,  which  regards  evil.— Secondly,  that  it  is 
future;  for  hope  does  not  regard  that  which  is  present  and 
already  possessed:  in  this  respect,  hope  differs  from  joy 
which  regards  a  present  good.- — Thirdly,  that  it  must  be 
something  arduous  and  difficult  to  obtain,  for  we  do  not 
speak  of  any  one  hoping  for  trifles,  which  are  in  one's  power 
to  have  at  any  time :  in  this  respect,  hope  differs  from  desire 
or  cupidity,  which  regards  the  future  good  absolutely: 
wherefore  it  belongs  to  the  concupiscible,  while  hope  belongs 
to  the  irascible  faculty. — Fourthly,  that  this  difficult  thing 
is  something  possible  to  obtain:  for  one  does  not  hope  for 
that  which  one  cannot  get  at  all:  and,  in  this  respect,  hope 
differs  from  despair.  It  is  therefore  evident  that  hope  differs 
from  desire,  as  the  irascible  passions  differ  from  the  con- 
cupiscible. For  this  reason,  moreover,  hope  presupposes 
desire:  just  as  all  the  irascible  passions  presuppose  the 
passions  of  the  concupiscible  faculty,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXV.,  A.  I). 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Augustine  mentions  desire  instead  of  hope, 
because  each  regards  future  good;  and  because  the  good 
which  is  not  arduous  is  reckoned  as  nothing :  thus  implying 
that  desire  seems  to  tend  chiefly  to  the  arduous  good,  to 
which  hope  tends  likewise. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  object  of  hope  is  the  future  good  con- 


HOPE  AND  DESPAIR  457 

sidered,   not   absolutely,  but   as   arduous   and   difficult   of 
attainment,  as  stated  above. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  object  of  hope  adds  not  only  possi- 
bility to  the  object  of  desire,  but  also  difficulty:  and  this 
makes  hope  belong  to  another  power,  viz.  the  irascible, 
which  regards  something  difficult,  as  stated  in  the  First 
Part  (Q.  LXXXL,  A.  2).  Moreover,  possibility  and  im- 
possibility are  not  altogether  accidental  to  the  object  of  the 
appetitive  power:  because  the  appetite  is  a  principle  of 
movement ;  and  nothing  is  moved  to  anything  except  under 
the  aspect  of  being  possible;  for  no  one  is  moved  to  that 
which  he  reckons  impossible  to  get.  Consequently  hope 
differs  from  despair  according  to  the  difference  of  possible 
and  impossible. 

Second  Article. 

whether  piope  is  in  the  apprehensive  or  in  the 
appetitive  power  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  hope  belongs  to  the  cognitive 
power.  Because  hope,  seemingly,  is  a  kind  of  awaiting; 
for  the  Apostle  says  (Rom.  viii.  25) :  If  we  hope  for  that  which 
we  see  not  ;  we  wait  for  it  with  patience.  But  awaiting  seems 
to  belong  to  the  cognitive  power,  which  we  exercise  by 
looking  out.     Therefore  hope  belongs  to  the  cognitive  power. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  Apparently  hope  is  the  same  as  confi- 
dence; hence  when  a  man  hopes  he  is  said  to  be  confident, 
as  though  to  hope  and  to  be  confident  were  the  same  thing. 
But  confidence,  like  faith,  seems  to  belong  to  the  cognitive 
power.     Therefore  hope  does  too. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  Certainty  is  a  property  of  the  cognitive 
power.  But  certainty  is  ascribed  to  hope.  Therefore  hope 
belongs  to  the  cognitive  power. 

On  the  contrary,  Hope  regards  good,  as  stated  above 
(A.  i).  Now  good,  as  such,  is  not  the  object  of  the  cognitive, 
but  of  the  appetitive  power.  Therefore  hope  belongs,  not 
to  the  cognitive,  but  to  the  appetitive  power. 

/  answer  that,  Since  hope  denotes  a  certain  stretching  out 


458  QUESTION  XL 

of  the  appetite  towards  good,  it  evidently  belongs  to  the 
appetitive  power;  since  movement  towards  things  belongs 
properly  to  the  appetite :  whereas  the  action  of  the  cognitive 
power  is  accomplished  not  by  a  movement  of  the  knower 
towards  things,  but  rather  according  as  the  things  known 
are  in  the  knower.  But  since  the  cognitive  power  moves 
the  appetite,  by  presenting  its  object  to  it;  there  arise  in 
the  appetite  various  movements  according  to  various 
aspects  of  the  apprehended  object.  For  the  apprehension 
of  good  gives  rise  to  one  kind  of  movement  in  the  appetite, 
while  the  apprehension  of  evil  gives  rise  to  another :  in  like 
manner  various  movements  arise  from  the  apprehension  of 
something  present  and  of  something  future;  of  something 
considered  absolutely,  and  of  something  considered  as 
arduous;  of  something  possible,  and  of  something  impossible. 
And  accordingly  hope  is  a  movement  of  the  appetitive 
power  ensuing  from  the  apprehension  of  a  future  good, 
difficult  but  possible  to  obtain ;  namely,  a  stretching  forth 
of  the  appetite  to  such  a  good. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Since  hope  regards  a  possible  good,  there 
arises  in  man  a  twofold  movement  of  hope;  for  a  thing 
may  be  possible  to  him  in  two  ways,  viz.  by  his  own  power, 
or  by  another's.  Accordingly  when  a  man  hopes  to  obtain 
something  by  his  own  power,  he  is  not  said  to  wait  for  it, 
but  simply  to  hope  for  it.  But,  properly  speaking,  he  is 
said  to  await  that  which  he  hopes  to  get  by  another's  help 
as  though  to  await  [exspectare)  implied  keeping  one's  eyes 
on  another  {ex  alio  spectare),  in  so  far  as  the  apprehensive 
power,  by  going  ahead,  not  only  keeps  its  eye  on  the  good 
which  man  intends  to  get,  but  also  on  the  thing  by  whose 
power  he  hopes  to  get  it;  according  to  Ecclus.  li.  lo:  / 
looked  for  the  succour  of  men.  Wherefore  the  movement  of 
hope  is  sometimes  called  expectation,  on  account  of  the 
preceding  inspection  of  the  cognitive  power. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  When  a  man  desires  a  thing  and  reckons 
that  he  can  get  it,  he  believes  that  he  will  get  it;  and  from 
this  belief  which  precedes  in  the  cognitive  power,  the  ensuing 
movement  is  called  confidence.     Because  the  movement  of 


HOPE  AND  DESPAIR  459 

the  appetite  takes  its  name  from  the  knowledge  that  pre- 
cedes it,  as  an  effect  from  a  cause  which  is  better  known ; 
for  the  apprehensive  power  knows  its  own  act  better  than 
that  of  the  appetite. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Certainty  is  ascribed  to  the  movement,  not 
only  of  the  sensitive,  but  also  of  the  natural  appetite;  thus 
we  say  that  a  stone  is  certain  to  tend  downwards.  This  is 
owing  to  the  inerrancy  which  the  movement  of  the  sensitive 
or  even  natural  appetite  derives  from  the  certainty  of  the 
knowledge  that  precedes  it. 

Third  Article, 
whether  hope  is  in  dumb  animals  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  is  no  hope  in  dumb  animals. 
Because  hope  is  for  some  future  good,  as  Damascene  says 
[De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.).  But  knowledge  of  the  future  is  not 
in  the  competency  of  dumb  animals,  whose  knowledge  is 
confined  to  the  senses  and  does  not  extend  to  the  future. 
Therefore  there  is  no  hope  in  dumb  animals. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  The  object  of  hope  is  a  future  good, 
possible  of  attainment.  But  possible  and  impossible  are  dif- 
ferences of  the  true  and  the  false,  which  are  only  in  the  mind, 
as  the  Philosopher  states  [Metaph.  vi.).  Therefore  there  is 
no  hope  in  dumb  animals,  since  they  have  no  mind. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Augustine  says  [Gen.  ad  lit.  ix.)  that 
animals  are  moved  by  the  things  that  they  see.  But  hope  is 
of  things  unseen  :/of  what  a  man  seeth,  why  doth  he  hope  for  .^ 
(Rom.  viii.  24).  Therefore  there  is  no  hope  in  dumb 
animals. 

On  the  contrary,  Hope  is  an  irascible  passion.  But  the 
irascible  faculty  is  in  dumb  animals.   Therefore  hope  is  also. 

/  answer  that,  The  internal  passions  of  animals  can  be 
gathered  from  their  outward  movements:  from  which  it  is 
clear  that  hope  is  in  dumb  animals.  For  if  a  dog  see  a  hare, 
or  a  hawk  see  a  bird,  too  far  off,  it  makes  no  movement 
towards  it,  having  no  hope,  as  it  were,  to  catch  it:  whereas, 


46o  QUESTION  XL 

if  it  be  near,  it  makes  a  movement  towards  it,  as  being  in 
hopes  of  catching  it.  Because,  as  stated  above  (Q.  L,  A.  2; 
Q.XXVI.,  A.  i;  Q.  XXXV.,  A.  i),  the  sensitive  appetite  of 
dumb  animals,  and  hkewise  the  natural  appetite  of  insensible 
things,  result  from  the  apprehension  of  an  intellect,  just  as  the 
appetite  of  the  intellectual  nature,  which  is  called  the  will. 
But  there  is  a  difference,  in  that  the  will  is  moved  by  an  ap- 
prehension of  the  intellect  in  the  same  subject;  whereas  the 
movement  of  the  natural  appetite  results  from  the  appre- 
hension of  the  separate  Intellect,  Who  is  the  Author  of 
nature;  as  does  also  the  sensitive  appetite  of  dumb  animals, 
who  act  from  a  certain  natural  instinct.  Consequently, 
in  the  actions  of  irrational  animals  and  of  other  natural 
things,  we  observe  a  procedure  which  is  similar  to  that 
which  we  observe  in  the  actions  of  art :  and  in  this  way  hope 
and  despaii-  are  in  dumb  animals. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Although  dumb  animals  do  not  know  the 
future,  yet  an  animal  is  moved  by  its  natural  instinct  to 
something  future,  as  though  it  foresaw  the  future.  Because 
this  instinct  is  planted  in  them  by  the  Divine  Intellect  that 
foresees  the  future. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  The  object  of  hope  is  not  the  possible  as 
differentiating  the  true,  for  thus  the  possible  ensues  from 
the  relation  of  a  predicate  to  a  subject.  The  object  of  hope 
is  the  possible  as  compared  to  a  power.  For  such  is  the 
division  of  the  possible  given  in  Metaph.  v.,  i.e.,  into  the 
two  kinds  we  have  just  mentioned. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Although  the  thing  which  is  future  does  not 
come  under  the  object  of  sight ;  nevertheless  through  seeing 
something  present,  an  animal's  appetite  is  moved  to  seek 
or  avoid  something  future. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  despair  is  contrary  to  hope  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 
Objectio7i  I.  It  seems  that  despair  is  not  contrary  to  hope. 
Because  to  one  thing  there  is  one  contrary  {Metaph.  x.).      But 


HOPE  AND  DESPAIR  461 

fear  is  contrary  to  hope.     Therefore  despair  is  not  contrary 
to  hope. 

Ohj.2.  Further,  contraries  seem  to  bear  on  the  same  thing. 
But  hope  and  despair  do  not  bear  on  the  same  thing :  since 
hope  regards  the  good,  whereas  despair  arises  from  some 
evil  that  is  in  the  way  of  obtaining  good.  Tlierefore  liope 
is  not  contrary  to  despair. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  movement  is  contrary  to  movement; 
while  repose  is  in  opposition  to  movement  as  a  privation 
thereof.  But  despair  seems  to  imply  immobility  rather  than 
movement.  Therefore  it  is  not  contrary  to  hope,  which 
implies  movement  of  stretching  out  towards  the  hoped-for 
good. 

On  the  contrary,  The  very  name  of  despair  (desperatio) 
implies  that  it  is  contrary  to  hope  (spes). 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXIIT,  A.  2),  there  is 
a  twofold  contrariety  of  movements.  One  is  in  respect  of 
approach  to  contrary  terms:  and  this  contrariety  alone  is 
to  be  found  in  the  concupiscible  passions,  for  instance 
between  love  and  hatred.  The  other  is  according  to  ap- 
proach and  withdrawal  with  regard  to  the  same  term; 
and  is  to  be  found  in  the  irascible  passions,  as  stated  above 
{loc.  cit.).  Now  the  object  of  hope,  which  is  the  arduous 
good,  has  the  character  of  a  principle  of  attraction,  if  it 
be  considered  in  the  light  of  something  attainable ;  and  thus 
hope  tends  thereto,  for  it  denotes  a  kind  of  approach.  But 
in  so  far  as  it  is  considered  as  unobtainable,  it  has  the 
character  of  a  principle  of  repulsion,  because,  as  stated  in 
Ethic,  iii.,  when  men  come  to  an  impossibility  they  disperse. 
And  this  is  how  despair  stands  in  regard  to  this  object, 
wherefore  it  implies  a  movement  of  withdrawal :  and  conse- 
quently it  is  contrary  to  hope,  as  withdrawal  is  to  approach. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Fear  is  contrary  to  hope,  because  their 
objects,  i.e.  good  and  evil,  are  contrary:  for  this  contrariety 
is  found  in  the  irascible  passions,  according  as  they  ensue 
from  the  passions  of  the  concupiscible.  But  despair  is  con- 
trary to  hope,  only  by  contrariety  of  approach  and  with- 
drawal. 


462  QUESTION  XL 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Despair  does  not  regard  evil  as  such;  some- 
times, however,  it  regards  evil  accidentally,  as  making  the 
difficult  good  impossible  to  obtain.  But  it  can  arise  from 
the  mere  excess  of  good. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Despair  implies  not  only  privation  of  hope, 
but  also  a  recoil  from  the  thing  desired,  by  reason  of  its 
being  esteemed  impossible  to  get.  Hence  despair,  like  hope, 
presupposes  desire ;  because  we  neither  hope  for  nor  despair 
of  that  which  we  do  not  desire  to  have.  For  this  reason,  too, 
each  of  them  regards  the  good,  which  is  the  object  of 
desire. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  experience  is  a  cause  of  hope  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  experience  is  not  a  cause  of 
hope.  Because  experience  belongs  to  the  cognitive  power; 
wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  ii.)  that  intellectual 
virtue  needs  experience  and  time.  But  hope  is  not  in  the 
cognitive  power,  but  in  the  appetite,  as  stated  above  (A.  2). 
Therefore  experience  is  not  a  cause  of  hope. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.)  that  the 
old  are  slow  to  hope,  on  account  of  their  experience  ;  whence  it 
seems  to  follow  that  experience  causes  want  of  hope.  But 
the  same  cause  is  not  productive  of  opposites.  Therefore 
experience  is  not  a  cause  of  hope. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  {De  Ccelo  ii.)  that 
to  have  something  to  say  ahout  everything,  without  leaving 
anything  out,  is  sometimes  a  proof  of  folly.  But  to  attempt 
everything  seems  to  point  to  great  hopes ;  while  folly  arises 
from  inexperience.  Therefore  inexperience,  rather  than 
experience,  seems  to  be  a  cause  of  hope. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.)  some  are 
hopeful,  through  having  been  victorious  often  and  over  many 
opponents  :  which  seems  to  pertain  to  experience.  Therefore 
experience  is  a  cause  of  hope. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  the  object  of  hope 
is  a  future  good,  difficult  but  possible  to  obtain.     Conse- 


HOPE  AND  DESPAIR  463 

quently  a  thing  may  be  a  cause  of  hope,  either  because  it 
makes  something  possible  to  a  man:  or  because  it  makes 
him  think  something  possible.  In  the  first  way  hope  is 
caused  by  ever3rthing  that  increases  a  man's  power;  e.g. 
riches,  strength,  and,  among  others,  experience:  since  by 
experience  man  acquires  the  possibility  of  getting  some- 
thing easily,  and  the  result  of  this  is  hope.  Wherefore 
Vegetius  says  (De  Re  Milit.):  No  one  fears  to  do  that  which 
he  is  sure  of  having  learnt  welL 

In  the  second  way,  hope  is  caused  by  everything  that 
makes  man  think  that  he  can  obtain  something:  and  thus 
both  teaching  and  persuasion  may  be  a  cause  of  hope.  And 
then  again  experience  is  a  cause  of  hope,  in  so  far  as  it 
makes  him  reckon  something  possible,  which  before  his  ex- 
perience he  looked  upon  as  impossible. — 'However,  in  this 
way,  experience  can  cause  a  lack  of  hope:  because  just  as  it 
makes  a  man  think  possible  what  he  had  previously  thought 
impossible;  so,  conversely,  experience  makes  a  man  con- 
sider as  impossible  that  which  hitherto  he  had  thought 
possible.  Accordingly  experience  causes  hope  in  two  ways; 
despair  in  one  way :  and  for  this  reason  we  may  say  rather 
that  it  causes  hope. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Experience  in  matters  pertaining  to  action 
not  only  produces  knowledge;  it  also  causes  a  certain  habit, 
by  reason  of  custom,  which  renders  the  action  easier.  More- 
over, the  intellectual  virtue  itself  adds  to  the  possibility  of 
acting  with  ease :  because  it  shows  something  to  be  possible ; 
and  thus  is  a  cause  of  hope. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  old  are  wanting  in  hope  because  of  their 
experience,  in  so  far  as  experience  makes  them  think  some- 
thing impossible.  Plence  he  adds  (ibid.)  that  many  evils 
have  befallen  them. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Folly  and  inexperience  can  be  a  cause  of 
hope  accidentally  as  it  were,  by  removing  the  knowledge 
which  would  help  one  to  judge  truly  a  thing  to  be  impossible. 
Wherefore  inexperience  is  a  cause  of  hope,  for  the  same 
reason,  as  experience  causes  lack  of  hope. 


464  QUESTION  XL 


Sixth  Articlp:. 

whether  hope  abounds  in  young  men  and 
drunkards  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  :  — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  youth  and  drunkenness  are  not 
causes  of  hope.  Because  hope  impHes  certainty  and  steadi- 
ness; so  much  so  that  it  is  compared  to  an -anchor  (Heb.  vi. 
19).  But  young  men  and  dnmkards  are  wanting  in  steadi- 
ness; since  their  minds  are  easily  changed.  Therefore  youth 
and  drunkenness  are  not  causes  of  hope. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  as  stated  above  (A.  5),  the  cause  of  hope 
is  chiefly  whatever  increases  one's  power.  But  youth  and 
drunkenness  are  united  to  weakness.  Therefore  they  are 
not  causes  of  hope. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  experience  is  a  cause  of  hope,  as  stated 
above  (A.  5).  But  youth  lacks  experience.  Therefore  it  is 
not  a  cause  of  hope. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.)  that 
drunken  men  are  hopeful :  and  {Rhet.  ii.)  that  the  young  are 
full  of  hope. 

I  answer  that,  Youth  is  a  cause  of  hope  for  three  reasons, 
as  the  Philosopher  states  in  Rhet.  iii. :  and  these  three  reasons 
may  be  gathered  from  the  three  conditions  of  the  good 
which  is  the  object  of  hope — namely,  that  it  is  future, 
arduous  and  possible,  as  stated  above  (A.  i).  For  youth 
has  much  of  the  future  before  it,  and  little  of  the  past:  and 
therefore  since  memory  is  of  the  past,  and  hope  of  the  future, 
it  has  little  to  remember,  and  lives  very  much  in  hope. — 
Again,  youths,  on  account  of  the  heat  of  their  nature,  are 
full  of  spirit;  so  that  their  heart  expands:  and  it  is  owing 
to  the  heart  being  expanded  that  one  tends  to  that  which  is 
arduous;  wherefore  youths  are  spirited  and  hopeful. — Like- 
wise, they  who  have  not  suffered  defeat,  nor  had  experience 
of  obstacles  to  their  efforts,  are  prone  to  count  a  thing 
possible  to  them.  Wherefore  youths,  through  inexperience 
of  obstacles  and  of  their  own  shortcomings,  easily  count  a 


HOPE  AND  DESPAIR  465 

thing  possible;  and  consequently  are  of  good  hope.  Two 
of  these  causes  are  also  in  those  who  are  under  the  influence 
of  drink — viz.,  heat  and  high  spirits,  on  account  of  wine, 
and  heedlessness  of  dangers  and  shortcomings. — For  the 
same  reason  all  foolish  and  thoughtless  persons  attempt 
everything  and  are  full  of  hope. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Although  youths  and  those  who  are  under 
the  influence  of  drink,  lack  steadiness  in  reality,  yet  they  are 
steady  in  their  own  estimation,  for  they  think  that  they  will 
steadily  obtain  that  which  they  hope  for. 

In  like  manner,  in  reply  to  the  Second  Objection,  we  must 
observe  that  young  people  and  those  who  are  under  the 
influence  of  drink,  are  indeed  unsteady  in  reality:  but,  in 
their  own  estimation,  they  are  capable,  for  they  know  not 
their  shortcomings. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Not  only  experience,  but  also  lack  of  ex- 
perience, is,  in  some  way,  a  cause  of  hope,  as  explained  above. 

Seventh  Article, 
whether  hope  is  a  cause  of  love  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  hope  is  not  a  cause  of  love. 
Because,  according  to  Augustine  (De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.),  love  is 
the  first  of  the  soul's  emotions.  But  hope  is  an  emotion  of 
the  soul.  Therefore  love  precedes  hope,  and  consequently 
hope  does  not  cause  love. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  desire  precedes  hope.  But  desire  is 
caused  by  love,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXV.,  A.  2).  Therefore 
hope,  too,  follows  love,  and  consequently  is  not  its  cause. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  hope  causes  pleasure,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXXII.,  A.  3).  But  pleasure  is  only  of  the  good  that 
is  loved.     Therefore  love  precedes  hope. 

On  the  contrary,  The  gloss  commenting  on  Matth.  i.  2, 
Ahraham  hegot  Isaac,  and  Isaac  begot  Jacob,  says,  i.e.,  faith 
begets  hope,  and  hope  begets  charity.  But  charity  is  love. 
Therefore  love  is  caused  by  hope. 

/  answer  that,  Hope  can  regard  two  things.     For  it  regards 

11.  I  ,  30 


466  QUESTION  XL 

as  its  object,  the  good  which  one  hopes  for.  But  since  the 
good  we  hope  for  is  something  difficult  but  possible  to 
obtain;  and  since  it  happens  sometimes  that  what  is  difficult 
becomes  possible  to  us,  not  through  ourselves  but  through 
others;  hence  it  is  that  hope  regards  also  that  by  which 
something  becomes  possible  to  us. 

In  so  far,  then,  as  hope  regards  the  good  we  hope  to  get, 
it  is  caused  by  love :  since  we  do  not  hope  save  for  that  which 
we  desire  and  love. — But  in  so  far  as  hope  regards  one 
through  whomx  something  becomes  possible  to  us,  love  is 
caused  by  hope,  and  not  vice  versa.  Because  by  the  very 
fact  that  we  hope  that  good  will  accrue  to  us  through  some- 
one, we  are  moved  towards  him  as  to  our  own  good;  and 
thus  we  begin  to  love  him.  Whereas  from  the  fact  that  we 
love  someone  we  do  not  hope  in  him,  except  accidentally, 
that  is,  in  so  far  as  we  think  that  he  returns  our  love. 
Wherefore  the  fact  of  being  loved  by  another  makes  us  hope 
in  him ;  but  our  love  for  him  is  caused  by  the  hope  we  have 
in  him. 

Wherefore  the  Replies  to  the  Objections  are  evident. 

Eighth  Article, 
whether  hope  is  a  help  or  a  hindrance  to  action  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  hope  is  not  a  help  but  a  hin- 
drance to  action.  Because  hope  implies  security.  But 
security  begets  negligence  which  hinders  action.  Therefore 
hope  is  a  hindrance  to  action. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  sorrow  hinders  action,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXXVII. ,  A.  3).  But  hope  sometimes  causes  sorrow: 
for  it  is  written  (Pro v.  xiii.  12)  Hope  that  is  deferred  afflict eth 
the  soul.     Therefore  hope  hinders  action. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  despair  is  contrary  to  hope,  as  stated 
above  (A.  4).  But  despair,  especially  in  matters  of  war, 
conduces  to  action;  for  it  is  written  (2  Kings  ii.  26),  that 
it  is  dangerous  to  drive  people  to  despair.  Therefore  hope 
has  a  contrary  effect,  namely,  by  hindering  action. 


HOPE  AND  DESPAIR  467 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  written  (i  Cor.  ix.  10)  that  he  that 
ploitgheth  should  plough  in  hope  .  .  .  to  receive  fruit :  and  iLe 
same  applies  to  all  other  actions. 

I  answer  that,  Hope  of  its  very  nature  is  a  help  to  action 
by  making  it  more  intense:  and  this  for  two  reasons.  First, 
by  reason  of  its  object,  which  is  a  good,  difficult  but  possible. 
For  the  thought  of  its  being  difficult  arouses  our  attention ; 
while  the  thought  that  it  is  possible  is  no  drag  on  our  effort. 
Hence  it  follows  that  by  reason  of  hope  man  is  intent  on  his 
action.  Secondly,  on  account  of  its  effect.  Because  hope, 
as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXII. ,  A.  3),  causes  pleasure;  which 
is  a  help  to  action,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXIII.,  A.  4). 
Therefore  hope  is  conducive  to  action. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Hope  regards  a  good  to  be  obtained; 
security  regards  an  evil  to  be  avoided.  Wherefore  security 
seems  to  be  contrary  to  fear  rather  than  to  belong  to  hope. 
Yet  security  does  not  beget  negligence,  save  in  so  far  as  it 
lessens  the  idea  of  difficulty:  whereby  it  also  lessens  the 
character  of  hope:  for  the  things  in  which  a  man  fears  no 
hindrance,  are  no  longer  looked  upon  as  difficult. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Hope  of  itself  causes  pleasure;  it  is  by  acci- 
dent that  it  causes  sorrow,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXXII., 
A.  3  ad  2). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Despair  threatens  danger  in  war,  on  account 
of  a  certain  hope  that  attaches  to  it.  For  they  who  despair 
of  flight,  strive  less  to  fly,  but  hope  to  avenge  their  death : 
and  therefore  in  this  hope  they  fight  the  more  bravely,  and 
consequently  prove  dangerous  to  the  foe. 


QUESTION  XLI. 

OF  FEAR,  IN  ITSELF. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider,  in  the  first  place,  fear ;  and,  secondly, 
daring.  With  regard  to  fear,  four  things  must  be  considered : 
(i)  Fear,  in  itself;  (2)  Its  object;  (3)  Its  cause;  (4)  Its  effect. 
Under  the  first  head  there  are  four  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  fear  is  a  passion  of  the  soul  ?  (2)  Whether  fear 
is  a  special  passion  ?  (3)  Whether  there  is  a  natural  fear  ? 
(4)  Of  the  species  of  fear. 

First  Article, 
whether  fear  is  a  passion  of  the  soul  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  fear  is  not  a  passion  of  the  soul. 
For  Damascene  says  {De  Fide  Orthod.  iii.)  that  fear  is  a 
power,  by  way  of  avo-ToX')] — i.e.,  of  contraction — desirous  of 
vindicating  nature.  But  no  virtue  is  a  passion,  as  is  proved 
in  Ethic,  ii.     Therefore  fear  is  not  a  passion. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  every  passion  is  an  effect  due  to  the 
presence  of  an  agent.  But  fear  is  not  of  something  present, 
but  of  something  future,  as  Damascene  declares  {De  Fide 
Orthod.  ii.).     Therefore  fear  is  not  a  passion. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  every  passion  of  the  soul,  is  a  movement 
of  the  sensitive  appetite,  in  consequence  of  an  apprehension 
of  the  senses.  But  sense  apprehends,  not  the  future  but 
the  present.  Since,  then,  fear  is  of  future  evil,  it  seems 
that  it  is  not  a  passion  of  the  soul. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  [De  Civ.  Dei  xiv.)  reckons  fear 
among  the  other  passions  of  the  soul. 

468 


OF  FEAR,  IN  ITSELF  469 

/  answer  that.  Among  the  other  passions  of  the  soul,  after 
sorrow,  fear  chiefly  has  the  character  of  passion.  For  as  we 
have  stated  above  (Q.  XXII.),  the  notion  of  passion  implies 
first  of  all  a  movement  of  a  passive  power — i.e.,  of  a  power 
whose  object  is  compared  to  it  as  its  active  principle:  since 
passion  is  the  effect  of  an  agent.  In  this  way,  both  to  feel 
and  to  understand  are  passions.  Secondly,  more  properly 
speaking,  passion  is  a  movement  of  the  appetitive  power; 
and  mxore  properly  still,  it  is  a  movem.ent  of  an  appetitive 
power  that  has  a  bodily  organ,  such  movement  being  accom- 
panied by  a  bodily  transmutation.  And,  again,  most 
properly  those  movements  are  called  passions,  which  imply 
some  deterioration.  Now  it  is  evident  that  fear,  since  it 
regards  evil,  belongs  to  the  appetitive  power,  which  of  itself 
regards  good  and  evil.  Moreover,  it  belongs  to  the  sensitive 
appetite :  for  it  is  accompanied  by  a  certain  transmutation — 
i.e.,  contraction — as  Damascene  says  [cf.  Ohj.  i).  Again, 
it  implies  relation  to  evil  as  overcoming,  so  to  speak,  some 
particular  good.  Wherefore  it  has  most  properly  the  char- 
acter of  passion  ;  less,  however,  than  sorrow,  which  regards 
the  present  evil:  because  fear  regards  future  evil,  which  is 
not  so  strong  a  motive  as  present  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Virtue  denotes  a  principle  of  action:  where- 
fore, in  so  far  as  the  interior  movements  of  the  appetitive 
faculty  are  principles  of  external  action,  they  are  called 
virtues.  But  the  Philosopher  denies  that  passion  is  a  virtue 
by  way  of  habit. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Just  as  the  passion  of  a  natural  body  is  due 
to  the  bodily  presence  of  an  agent,  so  is  the  passion  of  the 
soul  due  to  the  agent  being  present  to  the  soul,  although 
neither  corporally  nor  really  present :  that  is  to  say,  in  so  far 
as  the  evil  which  is  really  future,  is  present  in  the  appre- 
hension of  the  soul. 

Reply  Ohj.  3 .  The  senses  do  not  apprehend  the  future :  but 
from  apprehending  the  present,  an  animal  is  moved  by 
natural  instinct  to  hope  for  a  future  good,  or  to  fear  a  future 
evil. 


470  QUESTION  XLI 

Second  Article, 
whether  fear  is  a  special  passion  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  fear  is  not  a  special  passion. 
For  Augustine  says  (Qq.  83)  that  the  man  who  is  not  dis- 
traught by  fear,  is  neither  harassed  by  desire,  nor  woitnded 
by  sickness — i.e.,  sorrow — nor  tossed  about  in  transports  of 
empty  joys.  Wherefore  it  seems  that,  if  fear  be  set  aside,  all 
the  other  passions  are  removed.  Therefore  fear  is  not  a 
special  but  a  general  passion. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vi.)  that 
pursuit  and  avoidance  in  the  appetite  are  what  affirmation  and 
denial  are  in  the  intellect.  But  denial  is  nothing  special  in 
the  intellect,  as  neither  is  affirmation,  but  something 
common  to  many.  Therefore  neither  is  avoidance  anything 
special  in  the  appetite.  But  fear  is  nothing  but  a  kind  of 
avoidance  of  evil.     Therefore  it  is  not  a  special  passion. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  if  fear  were  a  special  passion,  it  would  be 
chiefly  in  the  irascible  part.  But  fear  is  also  in  the  con- 
cupiscible:  since  the  Philosopher  says  (Rhet.  ii.)  th.d±  fear  is 
a  kind  of  sorrow  ;  and  Damascene  says  {pe  Fide  Orthod.  iii.) 
that  fear  is  a  power  of  desire  :  and  both  sorrow  and  desire 
are  in  the  concupiscible  faculty,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXIII., 
A.  4).  Therefore  fear  is  not  a  special  passion,  since  it 
belongs  to  different  powers. 

On  the  contrary.  Fear  is  condivided  with  the  other  passions 
of  the  soul,  as  is  clear  from  Damascene  [De  Fide  Orthod.  ii). 

I  answer  that,  The  passions  of  the  soul  derive  their  species 
from  their  objects:  hence  that  is  a  special  passion,  which  has 
a  special  object.  Now  fear  has  a  special  object,  as  hope 
has.  For  just  as  the  object  of  hope  is  a  future  good,  difficult 
but  possible  to  obtain;  so  the  object  of  fear  is  a  future  evil, 
difficult  and  irresistible.  Consequently  fear  is  a  special 
passion. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  All  the  passions  of  the  soul  arise  from  one 
source,   viz.,  love,  wherein   they   are   connected  with   one 


OF  FEAR,  IN  ITSELF  471 

another.  By  reason  of  this  connection,  when  fear  is  put 
aside,  the  other  passions  of  the  soul  are  dispersed;  not 
however,  as  though  it  were  a  general  passion. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Not  every  avoidance  in  the  appetite  is  fear, 
but  avoidance  of  a  special  object,  as  stated.  Wherefoie, 
though  avoidance  be  something  common,  yet  fear  is  a  special 
passion. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Fear  is  nowise  in  the  concupiscible:  for  it 
regards  evil,  not  absolutely,  but  as  difficult  or  arduous,  so 
as  to  be  almost  unavoidable.  But  since  the  irascible  pas- 
sions arise  from  the  passions  of  the  concupiscible  faculty, 
and  terminate  therein,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXV.,  A.  i) ; 
hence  it  is  that  what  belongs  to  the  concupiscible  is  ascribed 
to  fear.  For  fear  is  called  sorrow^  in  so  far  as  the  object 
of  fear  causes  sorrow  when  present:  wherefore  the  Philoso- 
pher says  [loc.  cit.)  that  fear  Sivises  from  the  representation  of 
a  future  evil  which  is  either  corruptive  or  painful.  In  like 
manner  desire  is  ascribed  by  Damascene  to  fear,  because 
just  as  hope  arises  from  the  desire  of  good,  so  fear  arises  from 
avoidance  of  evil;  while  avoidance  of  evil  arises  from  the 
desire  of  good,  as  is  evident  from  what  has  been  said  above 
(Q.  XXV.,  A.  2;  Q.  XXIX.,  A.  2;  Q.  XXXVI. ,  A.  2). 

Third  Article, 
whether  there  is  a  natural  fear  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  there  is  a  natural  fear.  For 
Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  iii.)  that  there  is  a  natural 
fear,  through  the  soul  refusing  to  he  severed  from  the  hody. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  fear  arises  from  love,  as  stated  above 
(A.  2).  But  there  is  a  natural  love,  as  Dionysius  states 
{Div.  Nom.  iv.).     Therefore  there  is  also  a  natural  fear. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  fear  is  opposed  to  hope,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XL.,  A.  4.  ad  1).  But  there  is  a  hope  of  nature,  as  is 
evident  from  Rom.  iv.  18,  where  it  is  said  of  Abraham  that 
against  hope  of  nature,  he  helieved  in  hope  of  grace.  There- 
fore there  is  also  a  fear  of  nature. 


472  QUESTION  XLI 

On  the  contrary,  That  which  is  natural  is  common  to  things 
animate  and  inanimate.  But  fear  is  not  in  things  inanimate. 
Therefore  there  is  no  natural  fear. 

/  answer  that,  A  movement  is  said  to  be  natural,  because 
nature  inclines  thereto.  Now  this  happens  in  two  ways. 
First,  so  that  it  is  entirely  accomplished  by  nature,  without 
any  operation  of  the  apprehensive  faculty:  thus  to  have  an 
upward  movement  is  natural  to  fire,  and  to  grow  is  the 
natural  movement  of  animals  and  plants.— Secondly,  a 
movement  is  said  to  be  natural,  if  nature  inclines  thereto, 
though  it  be  accomplished  by  the  apprehensive  faculty 
alone:  since,  as  stated  above  (Q.  X.,  A.  i),  the  movements  of 
the  cognitive  and  appetitive  faculties  are  reducible  to  nature 
as  to  their  first  principle.  In  this  way,  even  the  acts  of  the 
apprehensive  power,  such  as  understanding,  feeling,  and 
remembering,  as  well  as  the  movements  of  the  animal 
appetite,  are  sometimes  said  to  be  natural. 

And  in  this  sense  we  may  say  that  there  is  a  natural  fear ; 
and  it  is  distinguished  from  non-natural  fear,  by  reason  of 
the  diversity  of  its  object.  For,  as  the  Philosopher  says 
(Rhet.  ii.),  there  is  a  fear  of  corriiptive  evil,  which  nature 
shrinks  from  on  account  of  its  natural  desire  to  exist;  and 
such  fear  is  said  to  be  natural.  Again,  there  is  a  fear  of 
painful  evil,  which  is  repugnant  not  to  nature,  but  to  the 
desire  of  the  appetite;  and  such  fear  is  not  natural.  In  this 
sense  we  have  stated  above  (Q.  XXVI.,  A.  i;  Q.  XXX. 
A.  3;  Q.  XXXI.,  A.  7)  that  love,  desire,  and  pleasure  are 
divisible  into  natural  and  non-natural. 

But  in  the  first  sense  of  the  word  nattiral,  we  must  observe 
that  certain  passions  are  sometimes  said  to  be  natural,  as 
love,  desire,  and  hope;  whereas  the  others  cannot  be  called 
natural.  The  reason  of  this  is  because  love  and  hatred, 
desire  and  avoidance,  imply  a  certain  inclination  to  pursue 
what  is  good  or  to  avoid  what  is  evil ;  which  inclination  is  to 
be  found  in  the  natural  appetite  also.  Consequently  there 
is  a  natural  love ;  while  we  may  also  speak  of  desire  and  hope 
as  being  even  in  natural  things  devoid  of  knowledge. — On 
the  other  hand,  the  other  passions  of  the  soul  denote  certain 


OF  FEAR,  IN  ITSELF  473 

movements,  whereto  the  natural  inchnation  is  nowise 
sufficient.  This  is  due  either  to  the  fact  that  perception  or 
knowledge  is  essential  to  these  passions  (thus  we  have  said 
that  apprehension  is  a  necessary  condition  of  pleasure  and 
sorrow),  w^herefore  things  devoid  of  knowledge  cannot  be 
said  to  take  pleasure  or  to  be  sorrowful :  or  else  it  is  because 
suchlike  movements  are  contrary  to  the  very  nature  of 
natural  inclination:  for  instance,  despair  flies  from  good  on 
account  of  some  difficulty;  and  fear  shrinks  from  repelhng  a 
contrary  evil;  both  of  which  are  contrary  to  the  inclination 
of  nature.  Wherefore  suchlike  passions  are  in  no  way 
ascribed  to  inanimate  beings. 
Thus  the  Replies  to  the  Objections  are  evident. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  the  species  of  fear  are  suitably  assigned  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  species  of  fear  are  un- 
suitably assigned  by  Damascene  (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.); 
namely,  laziness,  shamefacedness,  shame,  amazement,  stupor, 
and  anxiety.  Because,  as  the  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.), 
fear  regards  a  saddening  evil.  Therefore  the  species  of  fear 
should  correspond  to  the  species  of  sorrow.  Now  there  are 
four  species  of  sorrow,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXV.,  A.  8). 
Therefore  there  should  only  be  four  species  of  fear  corre- 
sponding to  them. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  that  which  consists  in  an  action  of  our 
own  is  in  our  power.  But  fear  regards  an  evil  that  surpasses 
our  power,  as  stated  above  (A.  2).  Therefore  laziness, 
shamefacedness,  and  shame,  which  regard  our  own  actions, 
should  not  be  reckoned  as  species  of  fear. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  fear  is  of  the  future,  as  stated  above 
(AA.  I,  2).  But  shame  regards  a  disgraceful  deed  already 
done,  as  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius,  De  Nat.  Horn,  xx.) 
says.     Therefore  shame  is  not  a  species  of  fear. 

Ohj.  4.  Further,  fear  is  only  of  evil.  But  amazement  and 
stupor  regard  great  and  unwonted  things,  whether  good  or 


474  QUESTION  XLI 

evil.  Therefore  amazement  and  stupor  are  not  species  of 
fear. 

Obj.  5.  Further,  Philosophers  have  been  led  by  amazement 
to  seek  the  truth,  as  stated  at  the  beginning  of  Metaph. 
But  fear  leads  to  flight  rather  than  to  search.  Therefore 
amazement  is  not  a  species  of  fear. 

On  the  contrary  suffices  the  authority  of  Damascene  and 
Gregory  of  Nyssa  [cf.  Ohjs.  i,  3). 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  2),  fear  regards  a  future 
evil  which  surpasses  the  power  of  him  that  fears,  so  that 
it  is  irresistible.  Now  man's  evil,  like  his  good,  may  be 
considered  either  in  his  action  or  in  external  things.  In  his 
action  he  has  a  twofold  evil  to  fear.  First,  there  is  the  toil 
that  burdens  his  nature:  and  hence  arises  laziness,  as  when 
a  man  shrinks  from  work  for  fear  of  too  much  toil. — Secondly, 
there  is  the  disgrace  which  damages  him  in  the  opinion  of 
others.  And  thus,  if  disgrace  is  feared  in  a  deed  that  is  yet 
to  be  done,  there  is  shamefacedness  ;  if,  however,  it  be  in  a 
deed  already  done,  there  is  shame. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  evil  that  consists  in  external  things 
may  surpass  man's  faculty  of  resistance  in  three  ways. 
First  by  reason  of  its  magnitude;  when,  that  is  to  say,  a 
man  considers  some  great  evil  the  extent  of  which  he  is 
unable  to  gauge:  and  then  there  is  amazement. — Secondly, 
by  reason  of  its  being  unwonted;  because,  to  wit,  some 
unwonted  evil  arises  before  us,  and  on  that  account  is  great 
in  our  estimation :  and  then  there  is  stupor,  which  is  caused 
by  the  representation  of  something  unwonted. — Thirdly,  by 
reason  of  its  being  unforeseen;  because,  to  wit,  it  cannot  be 
foreseen :  thus  future  misfortunes  are  feared,  and  fear  of  this 
kind  is  called  anxiety. 

Reply  Obj.  1.  Those  species  of  sorrow  given  above  are 
not  derived  from  the  diversit}^  of  objects,  but  from  the 
diversity  of  effects,  and  for  certain  special  reasons.  Conse- 
quently there  is  no  need  for  those  species  of  sorrow  to  corre- 
spond with  these  species  of  fear,  which  are  derived  from  the 
proper  division  of  the  object  of  fear  itself. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  A  deed  considered  as  being  actually  done. 


OF  FEAR,  IN  ITSELF  475 

is  in  the  power  of  the  doer.  But  it  is  possible  to  take  into 
consideration  something  connected  with  the  deed,  and  sur- 
passing the  faculty  of  the  doer,  for  which  reason  he  shrinks 
from  the  deed.  It  is  in  this  sense  that  laziness,  shamefaced- 
ness,  and  shame  are  reckoned  as  species  of  fear. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  past  deed  may  be  the  occasion  of  fear 
of  future  reproach  or  disgrace :  and  in  this  sense  shame  is  a 
species  of  fear. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  Not  every  amazement  and  stupor  are  species 
of  fear ;  but  that  amazement  which  is  caused  by  a  great  evil, 
and  that  stupor  which  arises  from  an  unwonted  evil. — Or 
else  we  may  say  that,  just  as  laziness  shrinks  from  the  toil 
of  external  work,  so  amazement  and  stupor  shrink  from  the 
difficulty  of  considering  a  great  and  unwonted  thing,  whether 
good  or  evil :  so  that  amazement  and  stupor  stand  in  relation 
to  the  act  of  the  intellect,  as  laziness  does  to  external  work. 

Reply  Ohj.  5.  He  who  is  amazed  shrinks  at  present  from 
forming  a  judgment  of  that  which  amazes  him,  fearing  to 
fall  short  of  the  truth,  but  inquires  into  the  future:  whereas 
he  w^ho  is  overcome  by  stupor  both  fears  to  judge  at  present, 
and  to  inquire  into  the  future.  Wherefore  amazement  is  a 
beginning  of  philosophical  research:  whereas  stupor  is  a 
hindrance  thereto. 


QUESTION  XLII. 

OF  THE  OBJECT  OF  FEAR. 

{In  Six  Articles. ) 

We  must  now  consider  the  object  of  fear:  under  which  head 
there  are  six  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  good  or  evil  is 
the  object  of  fear  ?  (2)  Whether  evil  of  nature  is  the  object 
of  fear  ?  (3)  Whether  the  evil  of  sin  is  an  object  of  fear  ? 
(4)  Whether  fear  itself  can  be  feared  ?  (5)  Whether  sudden 
things  are  especially  feared  ?  (6)  Whether  those  things  are 
more  feared  against  which  there  is  no  remedy  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  the  object  of  fear  is  good  or  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  good  is  the  object  of  fear.  For 
Augustine  says  (Qq.  83)  that  we  fear  nothing  save  to  lose 
what  we  love  and  possess,  or  not  to  obtain  that  which  we 
hope  for.  But  that  which  we  love  is  good.  Therefore  fear 
regards  good  as  its  proper  object. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  (Rhet.  ii.)  that  power 
and  to  be  above  another  is  a  thing  to  be  feared.  But  this  is  a 
good  thing.     Therefore  good  is  the  object  of  fear. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  there  can  be  no  evil  in  God.  But  we  are 
commanded  to  fear  God,  according  to  Ps.  xxxiii.  10:  Fear 
the  Lord,  all  ye  saints.  Therefore  even  the  good  is  an  object 
of  fear. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  [De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  that 
fear  is  of  future  evil. 

I  answer  that,  Fear  is  a  movement  of  the  appetitive  power. 

476 


OF  THE  OBJECT  OF  FEAR  477 

Now  it  belongs  to  the  appetitive  power  to  pursue  and  to 
avoid,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  vi. :  and  pursuit  is  of  good,  while 
avoidance  is  of  evil.  Consequently  whatever  movement  of 
the  appetitive  power  implies  pursuit,  has  some  good  for  its 
object:  and  whatever  movement  implies  avoidance,  has  an 
evil  for  its  object.  Wherefore,  since  fear  denotes  an  avoid- 
ance, in  the  first  place  and  of  its  very  nature  it  regards  evil 
as  its  proper  object. 

It  can,  however,  regard  good  also,  in  so  far  as  referrible 
to  evil.  This  can  be  in  two  ways.  In  one  way,  inasmuch 
as  an  evil  causes  privation  of  good.  Now  a  thing  is  evil  from 
the  very  fact  that  it  is  a  privation  of  some  good.  Wherefore, 
since  evil  is  shunned  because  it  is  evil,  it  follows  that  it  is 
shunned  because  it  deprives  one  of  the  good  that  one  pursues 
through  love  thereof.  And  in  this  sense  Augustine  says 
that  there  is  no  cause  for  fear,  save  loss  of  the  good  we  love. 

In  another  way,  good  stands  related  to  evil  as  its  cause : 
in  so  far  as  some  good  can  by  its  power  bring  harm  to  the 
good  we  love:  and  so,  just  as  hope,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XL., 
A.  7),  regards  two  things,  namely,  the  good  to  which  it 
tends,  and  the  thing  through  which  there  is  a  hope  of  obtain- 
ing the  desired  good;  so  also  does  fear  regard  two  things, 
namely,  the  evil  from  which  it  shrinks,  and  that  good,  which 
by  its  power,  can  inflict  that  evil.  In  this  way  God  is  feared 
by  man,  inasmuch  as  He  can  inflict  punishment,  spiritual 
or  corporal.  In  this  way,  too,  we  fear  the  power  of  man; 
especially  when  it  has  been  thwarted,  or  when  it  is  unjust, 
because  then  it  is  more  likely  to  do  us  a  harm. 

In  like  manner  one  fears  to  he  over  another,  i.e.,  to  lean  on 
another,  so  that  it  is  in  his  power  to  do  us  a  harm :  thus  a 
man  fears  another,  who  knows  him  to  be  guilty  of  a  crime, 
lest  he  reveal  it  to  others. 

This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Objections. 


478  QUESTION  XLII 


Second  Article, 
whether  evil  of  nature  is  an  object  of  fear  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It.  seems  that  evil  of  nature  is  not  an  object 
of  fear.  For  the  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.)  ihditfear  makes 
us  take  counsel.  But  we  do  not  take  counsel  about  things 
which  happen  naturally,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iii.  Therefore 
evil  of  nature  is  not  an  object  of  fear. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  natural  defects  such  as  death  and  the 
like  are  always  threatening  man.  If  therefore  suchlike 
evils  were  an  object  of  fear,  man  would  needs  be  always  in 
fear. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  nature  does  not  move  to  contraries. 
But  evil  of  nature  is  an  effect  of  nature.  Therefore  if  a  man 
shrinks  from  suchlike  evils  through  fear  thereof,  this  is  not 
an  effect  of  nature.  Therefore  natural  fear  is  not  of  the 
evil  of  nature;  and  yet  it  seems  that  it  should  be. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.)  that  the 
most  terrible  of  all  things  is  death,  which  is  an  evil  of  nature. 

I  answer  that,  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.),  fear  is 
caused  by  the  imagination  of  a  future  evil  which  is  either 
corruptive  or  painful.  Now  just  as  a  painful  evil  is  that 
which  is  contrary  to  the  will,  so  a  corruptive  evil  is  that 
which  is  contrary  to  nature:  and  this  is  the  evil  of  nature. 
Consequently  evil  of  nature  can  be  the  object  of  fear. 

But  it  must  be  observed  that  evil  of  nature  sometimes 
arises  from  a  natural  cause;  and  then  it  is  called  evil  of 
nature,  not  merely  from  being  a  privation  of  the  good  of 
nature,  but  also  from  being  an  effect  of  nature;  such  are 
natural  death  and  other  like  defects.  But  sometimes  evil 
of  nature  arises  from  a  non-natural  cause;  such  as  violent 
death  inflicted  by  an  assailant.  In  either  case  evil  of  nature 
is  feared  to  a  certain  extent,  and  to  a  certain  extent  not. 
For  since  fear  arises /row  the  imagination  of  future  evil,  as  the 
Philosopher  says  [loc.  cit.),  whatever  removes  the  imagina- 
tion of  the  future  evil,  removes  fear  also.     Now  it  may 


OF  THE  OBJECT  OF  FEAR  479 

happen  in  two  ways  that  an  evil,  considered  as  future,  may 
not  seem  great.  First,  through  being  remote  and  far  off: 
for,  on  account  of  the  distance,  such  a  thing  is  considered 
as  though  it  were  not  to  be  at  all.  Hence  we  either  do  not 
fear  it,  or  fear  it  but  little:  for,  as  the  Philosopher  says 
(Rhet.  ii.),  we  do  not  fear  things  that  are  very  far  off  ;  since  all 
know  that  they  shall  die,  hut  as  death  is  not  near,  they  heed  it 
not. — Secondly,  a  future  evil  is  considered  as  though  it  were 
not  to  be,  on  account  of  its  being  inevitable,  wherefore  we 
look  upon  it  as  already  present.  Hence  the  Philosopher 
says  (Rhet.  ii.)  that  those  who  are  already  on  the  scaffold,  are 
not  afraid,  seeing  that  they  are  on  the  very  point  of  a  death 
from  which  there  is  no  escape;  hiit  in  order  that  a  man  he 
afraid,  there  must  he  some  hope  of  escape  for  him. 

Consequently  evil  of  nature  is  not  feared  if  it  be  not 
apprehended  as  future:  but  if  evil  of  nature,  that  is  cor- 
ruptive, be  apprehended  as  near  at  hand,  and  yet  with  some 
hope  of  escape,  then  it  will  be  feared. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  evil  of  nature  sometimes  is  not  an  effect 
of  nature,  as  stated  above.  But  in  so  far  as  it  is  an  effect  of 
nature,  although  it  may  be  impossible  to  avoid  it  entirely, 
yet  it  may  be  possible  to  delay  it.  And  with  this  hope 
one  may  take  counsel  about  avoiding  it. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  evil  of  nature  ever  threatens,  yet 
it  does  not  always  threaten  from  near  at  hand:  and  conse- 
quently it  is  not  always  feared. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Death  and  other  defects  of  nature  are  the 
effects  of  the  common  nature ;  and  yet  the  individual  nature 
rebels  against  them  as  far  as  it  can.  Accordingly,  from  the 
inclination  of  the  individual  nature  arise  pain  and  sorrow 
for  suchlike  evils,  when  present;  fear  when  threatening  in 
the  future. 

Third  Article, 
whether  the  evil  of  sin  is  an  object  of  fear? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 
Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  the  evil  of  sin  can  be  an  object 
of  fear.     For  Augustine  says  on  the  canonical  Epistle  of 


48o  QUESTION  XLII 

John  [Tract,  ix.),  that  by  chaste  fear  man  J  ears  to  he  severed 
from  God.  Now  nothing  but  sin  severs  us  from  God;  accord- 
ing to  Isa.  lix.  2:  Your  iniquities  have  divided  between  you 
and  your  God.  Therefore  the  evil  of  sin  can  be  an  object 
of  fear. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Tully  says   [QucBst.   Tusc.  iv.)   that  we 

fear  when  they  are  yet  to  come,  those  things  which  give  us  fain 

when  they  are  present.     But  it  is  possible  for  one  to  be  pained 

or  sorrowful  on  account  of  the  evil  of  sin.     Therefore  one 

can  also  fear  the  evil  of  sin. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  hope  is  contrary  to  fear.  But  the  good 
of  virtue  can  be  the  object  of  hope,  as  the  Philosopher 
declares  [Ethic,  ix.) :  and  the  Apostle  says  (Gal.  v.  10): 
/  have  confidence  in  you  in  the  Lord,  that  you  will  not  be  of 
another  mind.     Therefore  fear  can  regard  evil  of  sin. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  shame  is  a  kind  of  fear,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XLL,  A.  4).  But  shame  regards  a  disgraceful  deed, 
which  is  an  evil  of  sin.     Therefore  fear  does  so  likewise. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.)  that  not 
all  evils  are  feared,  for  instance  that  someone  be  unjust  or  slow, 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XL.,  A.  i;  Q.  XLL, 
A.  2),  while  the  object  of  hope  is  a  future  good  difficult  but 
possible  to  obtain,  so  the  object  of  fear  is  a  future  evil, 
arduous  and  not  to  be  easily  avoided.  From  this  we  may 
gather  that  whatever  is  entirely  subject  to  our  power  and 
will,  is  not  an  object  of  fear;  and  that  nothing  gives  rise  to 
fear  save  what  is  due  to  an  external  cause.  Now  human  will 
is  the  proper  cause  of  the  evil  of  sin:  and  consequently  evil 
of  sin,  properly  speaking,  is  not  an  object  of  fear. 

But  since  the  human  will  may  be  inclined  to  sin  by  an 
extrinsic  cause:  if  this  cause  have  a  strong  power  of  in- 
clination, in  that  respect  a  man  may  fear  the  evil  of  sin, 
in  so  far  as  it  arises  from  that  extrinsic  cause:  as  when 
he  fears  to  dwell  in  the  company  of  wicked  men,  lest  he  be 
led  by  them  to  sin.  But,  properly  speaking,  a  man  thus 
disposed,  fears  the  being  led  astray  rather  than  the  sin  con- 
sidered in  its  proper  nature,  i.e.,  as  a  voluntary  act;  for 
considered  in  this  light  it  is  not  an  object  of  fear  to  him. 


OF  THE  OBJECT  OF  FEAR  481 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Separation  from  God  is  a  punishment  re- 
sulting from  sin:  and  every  punishment  is,  in  some  way, 
due  to  an  extrinsic  cause. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Sorrow  and  fear  agree  in  one  point,  since 
each  regards  evil:  they  differ,  however,  in  two  points. 
First,  because  sorrow  is  about  present  evil,  whereas  fear  is 
of  future  evil.  Secondly,  because  sorrow,  being  in  the  con- 
cupiscible  faculty,  regards  evil  absolutely;  wherefore  it  can 
be  about  any  evil,  great  or  small;  whereas  fear,  being  in 
the  irascible  part,  regards  evil  wdth  the  addition  of  a  certain 
arduousness  or  difficulty;  which  difficulty  ceases  in  so  far 
as  a  thing  is  subject  to  the  will.  Consequently  not  all  things 
that  give  us  pain  when  they  are  present,  make  us  fear  when 
they  are  yet  to  come,  but  only  some  things,  namely,  those 
that  are  difficult. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Hope  is  of  good  that  is  obtainable.  Now 
one  may  obtain  a  good  either  of  oneself,  or  through  another : 
and  so,  hope  may  be  of  an  act  of  virtue,  which  lies  within 
our  own  power.  On  the  other  hand,  fear  is  of  an  evil  that 
does  not  lie  in  our  own  power:  and  consequently  the  evil 
which  is  feared  is  always  from  an  extrinsic  cause;  while  the 
good,  that  is  hoped  for,  may  be  both  from  an  intrinsic  and 
from  an  extrinsic  cause. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XLL,  A.  4  ad  2,  3), 
shame  is  not  fear  of  the  very  act  of  sin,  but  of  the  disgrace 
or  ignominy  which  arises  therefrom,  and  which  is  due  to  an 
extrinsic  cause. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  fear  itself  can  be  feared  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  fear  cannot  be  feared.  For 
whatever  is  feared,  is  prevented  from  being  lost,  through 
fear  thereof:  thus  a  man  who  fears  to  lose  his  health,  keeps 
it,  through  fearing  its  loss.  If  therefore  a  man  be  afraid 
of  fear,  he  will  keep  himself  from  fear  by  being  afraid: 
which  seems  absurd. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  fear  is  a  kind  of  flight.     But  nothing 

II.  I  31 


482  QUESTION  XLII 

flies  from  itself.  Therefore  fear  cannot  be  the  object  of 
fear. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  fear  is  about  the  future.  But  fear  is 
present  to  him  that  fears.  Therefore  it  cannot  be  the 
object  of  his  fear. 

On  the  contrary,  A  man  can  love  his  own  love,  and  can 
grieve  at  his  own  sorrow.  Therefore,  in  like  manner,  he 
can  fear  his  own  fear. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  3),  nothing  can  be  an 
object  of  fear,  save  what  is  due  to  an  extrinsic  cause;  but 
not  that  which  ensues  from  our  own  will.  Now  fear  arises 
partly  from  an  extrinsic  cause,  and  is  partly  subject  to  the 
will.  It  is  due  to  an  extrinsic  cause,  in  so  far  as  it  is  a  passion 
resulting  from  the  imagination  of  an  imminent  evil.  In  this 
sense  it  is  possible  for  fear  to  be  the  object  of  fear,  i.e.,  a 
man  may  fear  lest  he  should  be  threatened  by  the  necessity 
of  fearing,  through  being  assailed  by  some  great  evil. — It 
is  subject  to  the  will,  in  so  far  as  the  lower  appetite  obeys 
reason;  wherefore  man  is  able  to  drive  fear  away.  In  this 
sense  fear  cannot  be  the  object  of  fear,  as  Augustine  says 
(Qq.  83).  Lest,  however,  anyone  make  use  of  his  argu- 
ments, in  order  to  prove  that  fear  cannot  at  all  be  the 
object  of  fear,  we  must  add  a  solution  to  the  same. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Not  every  fear  is  identically  the  same; 
there  are  various  fears  according  to  the  various  objects  of 
fear.  Nothing,  then,  prevents  a  man  from  keeping  himself 
from  fearing  one  thing,  by  fearing  another,  so  that  the  fear 
which  he  has  preserves  him  from  the  fear  which  he  has  not. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Since  fear  of  an  imminent  evil  is  not  iden- 
tical with  the  fear  of  the  fear  of  an  imminent  evil ;  it  does  not 
follow  that  a  thing  flies  from  itself,  or  that  it  is  the  same 
flight  in  both  cases. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  On  account  of  the  various  kinds  of  fear 
already  alluded  to  [ad  2)  a  man's  present  fear  may  have 
a  future  fear  for  its  object. 


OF  THE  OBJECT  OF  FEAR  483 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  sudden  things  are  especially  feared  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  unwonted  and  sudden  things 
are  not  especially  feared.  Because,  as  hope  is  about  good 
things,  so  fear  is  about  evil  things.  But  experience  con- 
duces to  the  increase  of  hope  in  good  things.  Therefore  it 
also  adds  to  fear  in  evil  things. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.)  that 
those  are  feared  most,  not  who  are  quick-tempered,  hut  who  are 
gentle  and  cunning.  Now  it  is  clear  that  those  who  are 
quick-tempered  are  more  subject  to  sudden  emotions. 
Therefore  sudden  things  are  less  to  be  feared. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  we  think  less  about  things  that  happen 
suddenly.  But  the  more  we  think  about  a  thing,  the 
more  we  fear  it;  hence  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  iii.)  that 
some  appear  to  he  courageous  through  ignorance,  hut  as  soon  as 
they  discover  that  the  case  is  different  from  what  they  expected, 
they  run  away.     Therefore  sudden  things  are  feared  less. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {Conf.  ii.) :  Fear  is  startled 
at  things  unwonted  and  sudden,  which  endanger  things  heloved, 
and  takes  forethought  for  their  safety. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  3;  Q.  XLL,  A.  2),  the 
object  of  fear  is  an  imminent  evil,  which  can  be  repelled, 
but  with  difficulty.  Now  this  is  due  to  one  of  two  causes: 
to  the  greatness  of  the  evil,  or  to  the  weakness  of  him  that 
fears;  while  unwontedness  and  suddenness  conduce  to  both 
of  these  causes.  First,  it  helps  an  imminent  evil  to  seem 
greater.  Because  all  material  things,  whether  good  or  evil, 
the  more  we  consider  them,  the  smaller  they  seem.  Conse- 
quently, just  as  sorrow  for  a  present  evil  is  mitigated  in 
course  of  time,  as  Tully  states  (QucFst.  Tusc.  iii.);  so,  too, 
fear  of  a  future  evil,  is  diminished  by  thinking  about  it 
beforehand. — Secondly,  unwontedness  and  suddenness  in- 
crease the  weakness  of  him  that  fears,  in  so  far  as  they  deprive 
him  of  the  remedies  with  which  he  might  otherwise  provide 


484  QUESTION  XLII 

himself  to  forestall  the  coming  evil,  were  it  not  for  the  evil 
taking  him  by  surprise. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  object  of  hope  is  a  good  that  it  is 
possible  to  obtain.  Consequently  whatever  increases  a 
man's  power,  is  of  a  nature  to  increase  hope,  and,  for  the 
same  reason,  to  diminish  fear,  since  fear  is  about  an  evil 
which  cannot  be  easily  repelled.  Since,  therefore,  experi- 
ence increases  a  man's  power  of  action,  therefore,  as  it 
increases  hope,  so  does  it  diminish  fear. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Those  who  are  quick-tempered  do  not  hide 
their  anger;  wherefore  the  harm  they  do  others  is  not  so 
sudden,  as  not  to  be  foreseen.  On  the  other  hand,  those 
who  are  gentle  or  cunning  hide  their  anger;  wherefore  the 
harm  which  may  be  impending  from  them,  cannot  be  fore- 
seen, but  takes  one  by  surprise.  For  this  reason  the 
Philosopher  says  that  such  men  are  feared  more  than  others. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Bodily  good  or  evil,  considered  in  itself, 
seems  greater  at  first.  The  reason  for  this  is  that  a  thing  is 
more  obvious  when  seen  in  juxtaposition  with  its  contrary. 
Hence  when  a  man  passes  unexpectedly  from  penury  to 
wealth,  he  thinks  more  of  his  wealth  on  account  of  his 
previous  poverty:  while,  on  the  other  hand,  the  rich  man 
who  suddenly  becomes  poor,  finds  poverty  all  the  more  dis- 
agreeable. For  this  reason  sudden  evil  is  feared  more, 
because  it  seems  more  to  be  evil. — However,  it  may  happen 
through  some  accident  that  the  greatness  of  some  evil  is 
hidden;  for  instance  if  the  foe  hides  himself  in  ambush: 
and  then  it  is  true  that  evil  inspires  greater  fear  through 
being  thought  much  about. 

Sixth  Article. 

whether  those  things  are  more  feared,  for  which 
there  is  no  remedy  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  those  things  are  not  more  to  be 
feared,  for  which  there  is  no  remedy.  Because  it  is  a  con- 
dition of  fear,  that  there  be  some  hope  of  safety,  as  stated 


OF  THE  OBJECT  OF  FEAR  485 

above  (A.  2).  But  an  evil  that  cannot  be  remedied  leaves 
no  hope  of  escape.  Therefore  such  things  are  not  feared 
at  all. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  there  is  no  remedy  for  the  evil  of  death: 
since,  in  the  natural  course  of  things,  there  is  no  return  from 
death  to  life.  And  yet  death  is  not  the  most  terrible  thing 
of  all,  as  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.).  Therefore  those 
things  are  not  feared  most,  for  which  there  is  no  remedy. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  i.)  that  a 
thing  which  lasts  long  is  no  better  than  that  which  lasts  but  one 
day  :  nor  is  that  which  lasts  for  ever  any  better  than  that  which 
is  not  everlasting  :  and  the  same  applies  to  evil.  But  things 
that  cannot  be  remedied  seem  to  differ  from  other  things, 
merely  in  the  point  of  their  lasting  long  or  for  ever.  Conse- 
quently they  are  not  therefore  any  more  to  be  feared. 

On  the  contrary,  the  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.)  that  those 
things  are  most  to  be  feared  which  le^hen  done  iiDrong  cannot 
be  flit  right,  .  .  .  or  for  which  there  is  no  help,  or  which  are  not 
easy. 

I  answer  that,  The  object  of  fear  is  evil:  consequently 
whatever  tends  to  increase  evil,  conduces  to  the  increase  of 
fear.  Now  evil  is  increased  not  only  in  its  species  of  evil, 
but  also  in  respect  of  circumstances,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XVIII.,  A.  3).  And  of  all  the  circumstances,  long- 
lastingness,  or  even  everlastingness,  seems  to  have  the 
greatest  bearing  on  the  increase  of  evil.  Because  things 
that  exist  in  time  are  measured,  in  a  way,  according  to  the 
duration  of  time :  wherefore  if  it  be  an  evil  to  suffer  some- 
thing for  a  certain  length  of  time,  we  should  reckon  the  evil 
doubled,  if  it  be  suffered  for  twice  that  length  of  time 
And,  accordingly,  to  suffer  the  same  thing  for  an  infinite 
length  of  time,  i.e.,  for  ever,  implies,  so  to  speak,  an  infinite 
increase.  Now  those  evils  which,  after  they  have  come, 
cannot  be  remedied  at  all,  or  at  least  not  easily,  are  consi- 
dered as  lasting  for  ever  or  for  a  long  time :  for  which  reason 
they  inspire  the  greatest  fear. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Remedy  for  an  evil  is  twofold.  One,  by 
which  a  future  evil  is  warded  off  from  coming.     If  such  a 


486  QUESTION  XLII 

remedy  be  removed,  there  is  an  end  to  hope  and  conse- 
quently to  fear ;  wherefore  we  do  not  speak  now  of  remedies 
of  that  kind.  The  other  remedy  is  one  by  which  an  already 
present  evil  is  removed :  and  of  such  a  remedy  we  speak  now. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  death  be  an  evil  without  remedy, 
yet,  since  it  threatens  not  from  near,  it  is  not  feared,  as 
stated  above  (A.  2). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  The  Philosopher  is  speaking  there  of  things 
that  are  good  in  themselves,  i.e.,  good  specifically.  And 
suchlike  good  is  no  better  for  lasting  long  or  for  ever:  its 
goodness  depends  on  its  very  nature. 


QUESTION  XLIIl. 

OF  THE  CAUSE  OF  FEAR. 

[In  Two  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  cause  of  fear :  under  which  head 
there  are  two  points  of  inquiry :  (i)  Whether  love  is  the  cause 
of  fear  ?     (2)  Whether  defect  is  the  cause  of  fear  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  love  is  the  cause  of  fear  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  love  is  not  the  cause  of  fear. 
For  that  which  leads  to  a  thing  is  its  cause,  ^wtfear  leads 
to  the  love  of  charity  as  Augustine  says  on  the  canonical 
epistle  of  John  {Tract,  ix.).  Therefore  fear  is  the  cause  of 
love,  and  not  conversely. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.)  that 
those  are  feared  most  from  whom  we  dread  the  advent  of  some 
evil.  But  the  dread  of  evil  being  caused  by  someone,  makes 
us  hate  rather  than  love  him.  Therefore  fear  is  caused  by 
hate  rather  than  by  love. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  it  has  been  stated  above  (Q.  XLIL,  A.  3) 
that  those  things  which  occur  by  our  own  doing  are  not 
fearful.  But  that  which  we  do  from  love,  is  done  from  our 
inmost  heart.     Therefore  fear  is  not  caused  by  love. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  (Qq.  83) :  There  can  he  no 
doubt  that  there  is  no  cause  for  fear  save  the  loss  of  what  we 
lovey  when  we  possess  it,  or  the  failure  to  obtain  what  we  hope 
for.  Therefore  all  fear  is  caused  by  our  loving  something: 
and  consequently  love  is  the  cause  of  fear. 

487 


488  •      QUESTION  XLIIT 

/  answer  that,  The  objects  of  the  soul's  passions  stand  in 
relation  thereto  as  the  forms  to  things  natural  or  artificial: 
because  the  passions  of  the  soul  take  their  species  from 
their  objects,  as  the  aforesaid  things  do  from  their  forms. 
Therefore,  just  as  whatever  is  a  cause  of  the  form,  is  a  cause 
of  the  thing  constituted  by  that  form,  so  whatever  is  a  cause, 
in  any  way  whatever,  of  the  object,  is  a  cause  of  the  passion. 
Now  a  thing  may  be  a  cause  of  the  object,  either  by  way 
of  efficient  cause,  or  by  way  of  material  disposition.  Thus 
the  object  of  pleasure  is  good  apprehended  as  suitable  and 
conjoined:  and  its  efficient  cause  is  that  which  causes  the 
conjunction,  or  the  suitableness,  or  goodness,  or  appre- 
hension of  that  good  thing;  while  its  cause  by  way  of 
material  disposition,  is  a  habit  or  any  sort  of  disposition  by 
reason  of  which  this  conjoined  good  becomes  suitable  or  is 
apprehended  as  such. 

Accordingly,  as  to  the  matter  in  question,  the  object  of 
fear  is  something  reckoned  as  an  evil  to  come,  near  at  hand 
and  difficult  to  avoid.  Therefore  that  which  can  inflict 
such  an  evil,  is  the  efficient  cause  of  the  object  of  fear,  and, 
consequently,  of  fear  itself.  While  that  which  renders  a 
man  so  disposed  that  a  thing  is  such  an  evil  to  him,  is  a 
cause  of  fear  and  of  its  object,  by  way  of  material  disposition. 
And  thus  it  is  that  love  causes  fear:  since  it  is  through  his 
loving  a  certain  good,  that  whatever  deprives  a  man  of  that 
good  is  an  evil  to  him,  and  that  consequently  he  fears  it  as 
an  evil. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XLII.,  A.  i),  fear,  of 
itself  and  in  the  first  place,  regards  the  evil  from  which  it 
recoils  as  being  contrary  to  some  loved  good :  and  thus  fear, 
of  itself,  is  born  of  love. — But,  in  the  second  place,  it  regards 
the  cause  from  which  that  evil  ensues:  so  that  sometimes, 
accidentally,  fear  gives  rise  to  love;  in  so  far  as,  for  instance, 
through  fear  of  God's  punishments,  man  keeps  His  com- 
mandments, and  thus  begins  to  hope,  while  hope  leads  to 
love,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XL.,  A.  7). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  He,  from  whom  evil  is  expected,  is  indeed 
hated  at  first;  but  afterwards,  when  once  we  begin  to  hope 


OF  THE  CAUSE  OF  FEAR  489 

for  good  from  him,  we  begin  to  love  him.  But  the  good, 
the  contrary  evil  of  which  is  feared,  was  loved  from  the 
beginning. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  This  argument  is  true  of  that  which  is  the 
efficient  cause  of  the  evil  to  be  feared:  whereas  love  causes 
fear  by  way  of  material  disposition,  as  stated  above. 

Second  Article, 
whether  defect  is  the  cause  of  fear  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  defect  is  not  a  cause  of  fear. 
Because  those  who  are  in  power  are  very  much  to  be  feared. 
But  defect  is  contrary  to  power.  Therefore  defect  is  not 
a  cause  of  fear. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  defect  of  those  who  are  already  being 
executed  is  extreme.  But  suchlike  do  not  fear  as  stated  in 
Rhet.  ii.     Therefore  defect  is  not  a  cause  of  fear. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  men  compete  with  one  another  from 
strength  not  from  defect.  But  those  who  contend  fear  those 
who  contend  with  them  (Rhet.  ii.).  Therefore  defect  is  not  a 
cause  of  fear. 

On  the  contrary,  Contraries  ensue  from  contrary  causes. 
But  wealth,  strength,  a  multitude  of  friends,  and  power  drive 
fear  away  [Rhet.  ii.) .   Therefore  fear  is  caused  by  lack  of  these. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  fear  may  be  set  down 
to  a  twofold  cause :  one  is  by  way  of  a  material  disposition, 
on  the  part  of  him  that  fears ;  the  other  is  by  way  of  efficient 
cause,  on  the  part  of  the  person  feared.  As  to  the  first  then, 
some  defect  is,  of  itself,  the  cause  of  fear :  for  it  is  owing  to 
some  lack  of  power  that  one  is  unable  easily  to  repulse  a 
threatening  evil.  And  yet,  in  order  to  cause  fear,  this  defect 
must  be  according  to  a  measure.  For  the  defect  which 
causes  fear  of  a  future  evil,  is  less  than  the  defect  caused  by 
evil  present,  which  is  the  object  of  sorrow.  And  still  greater 
would  be  the  defect,  if  perception  of  the  evil,  or  love  of  the 
good  whose  contrary  is  feared,  were  entirely  absent. 

But  as  to  the  second,  power  and  strength  are,  of  them- 


490  QUESTION  XLIll 

selves,  the  cause  of  fear:  because  it  is  owing  to  the  fact  that 
the  cause  apprehended  as  harmful  is  powerful,  that  its 
effect  cannot  be  repulsed.  It  may  happen,  however,  in 
this  respect,  that  some  defect  causes  fear  accidentally,  in 
so  far  as  owing  to  some  defect  someone  wishes  to  hurt 
another;  for  instance,  by  reason  of  injustice,  or  because  that 
other  has  already  done  him  a  harm,  or  because  he  fears  to 
be  harmed  by  him. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  argument  is  true  of  the  cause  of  fear, 
on  the  part  of  the  efficient  cause. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Those  who  are  already  being  executed,  are 
actually  suffering  from  a  present  evil;  wherefore  their 
defect  exceeds  the  measure  of  fear. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Those  who  contend  with  one  another  are 
afraid,  not  on  account  of  the  power  which  enables  them 
to  contend  :  but  on  account  of  the  lack  of  power,  owing  to 
which  they  are  not  confident  of  victory. 


QUESTION  XLIV. 

OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  FEAR. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  effects  of  fear :  under  which  head 
there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  fear  causes 
contraction  ?  (2)  Whether  it  makes  men  suitable  for 
counsel  ?  (3)  Whether  it  makes  one  tremble  ?  (4)  Whether 
it  hinders  action  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  fear  causes  contraction  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  fear  does  not  cause  contraction. 
For  when  contraction  takes  place,  the  heat  and  vital  spirits 
are  withdrawn  inwardly.  But  accumulation  of  heat  and 
vital  spirits  in  the  interior  parts  of  the  body,  dilates  the  heart 
unto  endeavours  of  daring,  as  may  be  seen  in  those  who  are 
angered:  while  the  contrary  happens  in  those  who  are 
afraid.     Therefore  fear  does  not  cause  contraction. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  when,  as  a  result  of  contraction,  the 
vital  spirits  and  heat  are  accumulated  in  the  interior 
parts,  man  cries  out,  as  may  be  seen  in  those  who  are 
in  pain.  But  those  who  fear  utter  nothing  :  on  the  con- 
trary they  lose  their  speech.  Therefore  fear  does  not 
cause  contraction. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  shame  is  a  kind  of  fear,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XLI.,  A.  4).  But  those  who  are  ashamed  blush,  as  Tully 
{Quaest.  Tusc.  iv.),  and  the  Philosopher  (Ethic,  iv.)  observe. 
But    blushing   is   an   indication,   not   of    contraction,   but 

491 


492  QUESTION  XLIV 

of  the  reverse.     Therefore  contraction  is  not  an  effect  of 
fear. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  (De  Fide  Orthod.  iii.) 
that  fear  is  a  power  according  to  avaroXr],  i.e.,  contrac- 
tion. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXVIIL,  A.  5),  in  the 
passions  of  the  soul,  the  formal  element  is  the  movement  of 
the  appetitive  power,  while  the  bodily  transmutation  is  the 
material  element.  Both  of  these  are  mutually  proportionate ; 
and  consequently  the  bodily  transmutation  assumes  a  resem- 
blance to  and  the  very  nature  of  the  appetitive  movement. 
Now,  as  to  the  appetitive  movement  of  the  soul,  fear  implies 
a  certain  contraction :  the  reason  of  which  is  that  fear  arises 
from  the  imagination  of  some  threatening  evil  which  is 
difficult  to  repel,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XLL,  A.  2).  But  that 
a  thing  be  difficult  to  repel  is  due  to  lack  of  power,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XLIIL,  A.  2):  and  the  weaker  a  power  is,  the 
fewer  the  things  to  which  it  extends.  Wherefore  from  the 
very  imagination  that  causes  fear  there  ensues  a  certain 
contraction  in  the  appetite.  Thus  w^e  observe  in  one  who 
is  dying  that  nature  withdraws  inwardly,  on  account  of  the 
lack  of  power:  and  again  we  see  the  inhabitants  of  a  city, 
when  seized  with  fear,  leave  the  outskirts,  and,  as  far  as 
possible,  make  for  the  inner  quarters.  It  is  in  resemblance 
to  this  contraction,  which  pertains  to  the  appetite  of  the 
soul,  that  in  fear  a  similar  contraction  of  heat  and  vital 
spirits  towards  the  inner  parts  takes  place  in  regard  to  the 
body. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  the  Philosopher  says  [Problem,  xxvii.), 
although  in  those  who  fear,  the  vital  spirits  recede  from  the 
outer  to  the  inner  parts  of  the  body,  yet  the  movement  of 
vital  spirits  is  not  the  same  in  those  who  are  angry  and 
those  who  are  afraid.  For  in  those  who  are  angry,  by  reason 
of  the  heat  and  subtlety  of  the  vital  spirits,  which  result 
from  the  craving  for  vengeance,  the  inward  movement  has 
an  upward  direction:  wherefore  the  vital  spirits  and  heat 
concentrate  around  the  heart :  the  result  being  that  an  angry 
man  is  quick  and  brave  in  attacking. — But  in  those  who 


OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  FEAR  493 

are  afraid,  on  account  of  the  condensation  caused  by  the 
cold,  the  vital  spirits  have  a  downward  movement ;  the  said 
cold  being  due  to  the  imagined  lack  of  power.  Consequently 
the  heat  and  vital  spirits  abandon  the  heart  instead  of  con- 
centrating around  it:  the  result  being  that  a  man  who  is 
afraid  is  not  quick  to  attack,  but  is  more  inclined  to  run 
away. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  To  everyone  that  is  in  pain,  whether  man 
or  animal,  it  is  natural  to  use  all  possible  means  of  repelling 
the  harmful  thing  that  causes  pain  by  its  presence :  thus 
we  observe  that  animals,  when  in  pain,  attack  with  their  jaws 
or  with  their  horns.  Now  the  greatest  help  for  all  purposes, 
in  animals,  is  heat  and  vital  spirits:  wherefore  when  they 
are  in  pain,  their  nature  stores  up  the  heat  and  vital  spirits 
within  them,  in  order  to  make  use  thereof  in  repelling  the 
harmful  object.  Hence  the  Philosopher  says  {Problem. 
xxvii.)  when  the  vital  spirits  and  heat  are  concentrated 
together  within,  they  require  to  find  a  vent  in  the  voice: 
for  which  reason  those  who  are  in  pain  can  scarcely  refrain 
from  crying  aloud. — On  the  other  hand,  in  those  who  are 
afraid,  the  internal  heat  and  vital  spirits  move  from  the 
heart  downwards,  as  stated  above  {ad  i) :  wherefore  fear 
hinders  speech  which  ensues  from  the  emission  of  the  vital 
spirits  in  an  upward  direction  through  the  mouth :  the  result 
being  that  fear  makes  its  subject  speechless.  For  this 
reason,  too,  fear  makes  its  subject  tremble,  as  the  Philosopher 
says  {Problem,  xxvii.). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Mortal  perils  are  contrary  not  only  to  the 
animal  appetite,  but  also  to  nature.  Consequently  in  such- 
like fear,  there  is  contraction  not  only  in  the  appetite,  but 
also  in  the  corporeal  nature:  for  when  an  animal  is  moved 
by  the  imagination  of  death,  it  experiences  a  contraction  of 
heat  towards  the  inner  parts  of  the  body,  as  though  it  were 
threatened  by  a  natural  death.  Hence  it  is  that  those  who 
are  in  fear  of  death  turn  pale  {Ethic,  iv.). — But  the  evil  that 
shame  fears,  is  contrary,  not  to  nature,  but  only  to  the 
appetite  of  the  soul.  Consequently  there  results  a  contrac- 
tion in  this  appetite,  but  not  in  the  corporeal  nature;  in 


494  QUESTION  XLTV 

fact,  the  soul,  as  though  contracted  in  itself,  is  free  to  set 
the  vital  spirits  and  heat  in  movement,  so  that  they  spread 
to  the  outward  parts  of  the  body :  the  result  being  that  those 
who  are  ashamed  blush. 


Second  Article, 
whether  fear  makes  one  suitable  for  counsel  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  fear  does  not  make  one  suitable 
for  counsel.  For  the  same  thing  cannot  be  conducive  to 
counsel,  and  a  hindrance  thereto.  But  fear  hinders  counsel: 
because  every  passion  disturbs  repose,  which  is  requisite 
for  the  good  use  of  reason.  Therefore  fear  does  not  make 
a  man  suitable  for  counsel. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  counsel  is  an  act  of  reason,  in  thinking 
and  deliberating  about  the  future.  But  a  certain  fear 
drives  away  all  thought,  and  dislocates  the  mind,  as  Tully 
observes  (Quaest.  Tusc.  iv.).  Therefore  fear  does  not  con- 
duce to  counsel,  but  hinders  it. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  just  as  we  have  recourse  to  counsel  in 
order  to  avoid  evil,  so  do  we,  in  order  to  attain  good  things. 
But  whereas  fear  is  of  evil  to  be  avoided,  so  is  hope  of 
good  things  to  be  obtained.  Therefore  fear  is  not  more  con- 
ducive to  counsel,  than  hope  is. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Rhet.  ii.)  that  fear 
makes  men  of  counsel. 

I  answer  that,  A  man  of  counsel  may  be  taken  in  two 
ways.  First,  from  his  being  willing  or  anxious  to  take 
counsel.  And  thus  fear  makes  men  of  counsel.  Because, 
as  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iii.),  we  take  counsel  on  great 
matters,  because  therein  we  distrust  ourselves.  Now  things 
which  make  us  afraid,  are  not  simply  evil,  but  have  a 
certain  magnitude,  both  because  they  seem  difficult  to 
repel,  and  because  they  are  apprehended  as  near  to  us,  as 
stated  above  (Q.  XLIL,  A.  2).  Wherefore  men  seek  for 
counsel  especially  when  they  are  afraid. 

Secondly,  a  man  of    counsel,  means  one  who  is  apt  for 


OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  FEAR  495 

giving  good  counsel:  and  in  this  sense,  neither  fear  nor  any 
passion  makes  men  of  counsel.  Because  when  a  man  is 
affected  by  a  passion,  things  seem  to  him  greater  or  smaller 
than  they  really  are:  thus  to  a  lover,  what  he  loves  seems 
better;  to  him  that  fears,  what  he  fears  seems  more  dreadful. 
Consequently  owing  to  the  want  of  right  judgment,  every 
passion,  considered  in  itself,  hinders  the  faculty  of  giving 
good  counsel. 

This  suffices  for  the  Reply  to  the  First  Objection. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  stronger  a  passion  is,  the  greater 
hindrance  is  it  to  the  man  who  is  swayed  by  it.  Conse- 
quently, when  fear  is  intense,  man  does  indeed  wish  to  take 
counsel,  but  his  thoughts  are  so  disturbed,  that  he  can 
find  no  counsel.  If,  however,  the  fear  be  slight,  so  as 
to  make  a  man  wish  to  take  counsel,  without  gravely 
disturbing  the  reason;  it  may  even  make  it  easier  for  him 
to  take  good  counsel,  by  reason  of  its  making  him  wishful 
to  do  so. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Hope  also  makes  man  a  good  counsellor: 
because,  as  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.),  no  man  takes 
counsel  in  matters  he  despairs  of,  nor  about  impossible  things, 
as  he  says  in  Ethic,  iii.  But  fear  incites  to  counsel  more  than 
hope  does.  Because  hope  is  of  good  things,  as  being  possible 
of  attainment ;  whereas  fear  is  of  evil  things,  as  being  difficult 
to  repel,  so  that  fear  regards  the  aspect  of  difficulty  more 
than  hope  does.  And  it  is  in  matters  of  difficulty,  especially 
when  we  distrust  ourselves,  that  we  take  counsel,  as  stated 
above. 

Third  Article, 
whether  fear  makes  one  tremble  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  trembling  is  not  an  effect  of 
fear.  Because  trembling  is  occasioned  by  cold;  thus  we 
observe  that  a  cold  person  trembles.  Now  fear  does  not 
seem  to  make  one  cold,  but  rather  to  cause  a  parching  heat : 
a  sign  whereof  is  that  those  who  fear  are  thirsty,  especially 
if  their  fear  be  very  great,  as  in  the  case  of  those  who  are 


496  QUESTION  XLIV 

being  led  to  execution.  Therefore  fear  does  not  cause 
trembling. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  faecal  evacuation  is  occasioned  by  heat; 
hence  laxative  medicines  are  generally  warm.  But  these 
evacuations  are  often  caused  by  fear.  Therefore  fear 
apparently  causes  heat;  and  consequently  does  not  cause 
trembling. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  in  fear,  the  heat  is  withdrawn  from  the 
outer  to  the  inner  parts  of  the  body.  If,  therefore,  man 
trembles  in  his  outw^ard  parts,  through  the  heat  being  with- 
drawn thus;  it  seems  that  fear  should  cause  this  trembling 
in  all  the  external  members.  But  such  is  not  the  case. 
Therefore  trembling  of  the  body  is  not  caused  by  fear. 

On  the  contrary,  TuUy  says  (Quaest.  Tusc.  iv.)  that  fear 
is  followed  by  trembling,  pallor  and  chattering  of  the  teeth. 

I  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (A.  i),  in  fear  there  takes 
place  a  certain  contraction  from  the  outward  to  the  inner 
parts  of  the  body,  the  result  being  that  the  outer  parts 
become  cold;  and  for  this  reason  trembling  is  occasioned  in 
these  parts,  being  caused  by  a  lack  of  power  in  controlling 
the  members:  which  lack  of  power  is  due  to  the  want  of 
heat,  which  is  the  instrument  whereby  the  soul  moves  those 
members,  as  stated  in  De  Anima  ii. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  When  the  heat  withdraws  from  the  outer 
to  the  inner  parts,  the  inward  heat  increases,  especially  in 
the  inferior  or  nutritive  parts.  Consequently  the  humid 
element  being  spent,  thirst  ensues;  sometimes  indeed  the 
result  is  a  loosening  of  the  bowels,  and  urinary  or  even 
seminal  evacuation. — Or  else  suchlike  evacuations  are  due 
to  contraction  of  the  abdomen  and  testicles,  as  the  Philoso- 
pher says  [Problem,  xxii.). 

This  suffices  for  the  Reply  to  the  Second  Objection. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  In  fear,  heat  abandons  the  heart,  with  a 
downward  movement:  hence  in  those  who  are  afraid  the 
heart  especially  trembles,  as  also  those  members  which  are 
connected  with  the  breast  where  the  heart  resides.  Hence 
those  who  fear  tremble  especially  in  their  speech,  on  account 
of  the  tracheal  artery  being  near  the  heart.     The  lower  lip, 


OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  FEAR  497 

too,  and  the  lower  jaw  tremble,  through  their  connection 
with  the  heart;  which  explains  the  chattering  of  the  teeth. 
For  the  same  reason  the  arms  and  hands  tremble. — Or  else 
because  the  aforesaid  members  are  more  mobile.  For 
which  reason  the  knees  tremble  in  those  who  are  afraid, 
according  to  Isa.  xxxv.  3 :  Strengthen  ye  the  feeble  hands, 
and  confirm  the  trembling  (Vulg.,  weak)  knees. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  fear  hinders  action  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  fear  hinders  action.  For  action 
is  hindered  chiefly  by  a  disturbance  in  the  reason,  which 
directs  action.  But  fear  disturbs  reason,  as  stated  above 
(A.  2).     Therefore  fear  hinders  action. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  those  who  fear  while  doing  anything,  are 
more  apt  to  fail:  thus  a  man  who  walks  on  a  plank  placed 
aloft,  is  likely  to  fall  through  fear;  whereas,  if  he  were  to 
walk  on  the  same  plank  down  below,  he  would  not  fall, 
through  not  being  afraid.     Therefore  fear  hinders  action. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  laziness  or  sloth  is  a  kind  of  fear.  But 
laziness  hinders  action.     Therefore  fear  does  too. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Apostle  says  (Phil.  ii.  12) :  With  fear 
and  trembling  work  out  your  salvation  :  and  he  would  not  say 
this  if  fear  were  a  hindrance  to  a  good  work.  Therefore 
fear  does  not  hinder  a  good  action. 

I  answer  that,  Man's  exterior  actions  are  caused  by  the 
soul  as  first  mover,  but  by  the  bodily  members  as  instru- 
ments. Now  action  may  be  hindered  both  by  defect  of  the 
instrument,  and  by  defect  of  the  principal  mover.  On  the 
part  of  the  bodily  instruments,  fear,  considered  in  itself, 
is  always  apt  to  hinder  exterior  action,  on  account  of  the 
outward  members  being  deprived,  through  fear,  of  their 
heat.  But  on  the  part  of  the  soul,  if  the  fear  be  moderate, 
without  much  disturbance  of  the  reason,  it  conduces  to 
working  well,  in  so  far  as  it  causes  a  certain  solicitude,  and 
makes  a  man  take  counsel  and  work  with  greater  attention. 

II.  I  32 


498  QUESTION  XLIV 

— If,  however,  fear  increases  so  much  as  to  disturb  the 
reason,  it  hinders  action  even  on  the  part  of  the  soul.  But 
of  such  a  fear  the  Apostle  does  not  speak. 

This  suffices  for  the  Reply  to  the  First  Objection. 

Re'ply  Ohj.  2.  He  that  falls  from  a  plank  placed  aloft, 
suffers  a  disturbance  of  his  imagination,  through  fear  of  the 
fall  that  is  pictured  to  his  imagination. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Everyone  in  fear  shuns  that  which  he  fears: 
and  therefore,  since  laziness  is  a  fear  of  work  itself  as  being 
toilsome,  it  hinders  work  by  withdrawing  the  will  from  it. 
But  fear  of  other  things  conduces  to  action,  in  so  far  as  it 
inclines  the  will  to  do  that  whereby  a  man  escapes  from 
what  he  fears. 


QUESTION  XLV. 

OF  DARING. 

[In  Foiir  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  daring:  under  which  head  there  are 
four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  daring  is  contrary  to 
fear  ?  (2)  How  is  daring  related  to  hope  ?  (3)  Of  the 
cause  of  daring:  (4)  Of  its  effect. 

First  Article, 
whether  daring  is  contrary  to  fear  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  daring  is  not  contrary  to  fear. 
For  Augustine  says  (Qq.  83)  that  daring  is  a  vice.  Now 
vice  is  contrary  to  virtue.  Since,  therefore,  fear  is  not  a 
virtue  but  a  passion,  it  seems  that  daring  is  not  contrary  to 
fear. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  to  one  thing  there  is  one  contrary.  But 
hope  is  contrary  to  fear.  Therefore  daring  is  not  contrary 
to  fear. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  every  passion  excludes  its  opposite. 
But  fear  excludes  safety;  for  Augustine  says  [Conf.  ii.)  that 
fear  takes  forethought  for  safety.  Therefore  safety  is  contrary 
to  fear.     Therefore  daring  is  not  contrary  to  fear. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.)  that 
daring  is  contrary  to  fear. 

I  answer  that,  It  is  of  the  essence  of  contraries  to  be 
farthest  removed  from  one  another,  as  stated  in  Metaph.  x. 
Now  that  which  is  farthest  removed  from  fear,  is  daring: 

499 


500  QUESTION  XLV 

since  fear  turns  away  from  the  future  hurt,  on  account  of 
its  victory  over  him  that  fears  it;  whereas  daring  turns  on 
threatened  danger,  because  of  its  own  victory  over  that 
same  danger.  Consequently  it  is  evident  that  daring  is 
contrary  to  fear. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  Anger,  daring  and  all  the  names  of  the 
passions  can  be  taken  in  two  ways.  First,  as  denoting 
absolutely  movements  of  the  sensitive  appetite  in  respect 
of  some  object,  good  or  bad:  and  thus  they  are  names  of 
passions. — Secondly,  as  denoting  besides  this  movement, 
a  straying  from  the  order  of  reason:  and  thus  they  are 
names  of  vices.  It  is  in  this  sense  that  Augustine  speaks 
of  daring:  but  we  are  speaking  of  it  in  the  first  sense. 

Reply  Ohj,  2.  To  one  thing,  in  the  same  respect,  there  are 
not  several  contraries.  Accordingly  it  has  been  said  above 
(Q.  XXIII.,  A.  2;  Q.  XL.,  A.  4)  that  the  irascible  passions 
admit  of  a  twofold  contrariety:  one,  according  to  the 
opposition  of  good  and  evil,  and  thus  fear  is  contrary  to 
hope:  the  other,  according  to  the  opposition  of  approach 
and  withdrawal,  and  thus  daring  is  contrary  to  fear,  and 
despair  contrary  to  hope. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Safety  does  not  denote  soinething  contrary 
to  fear,  but  merely  the  exclusion  of  fear :  for  he  is  said  to  be 
safe,  who  fears  not.  Wherefore  safety  is  opposed  to  fear, 
as  a  privation :  while  daring  is  opposed  thereto  as  a  contrary. 
And  as  contrariety  implies  privation,  so  daring  implies 
safety. 

Second  Article, 
whether  daring  ensues  from  hope  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Ohjection  i.  It  seems  that  daring  does  not  ensue  from 
hope.  Because  daring  regards  evil  and  fearful  things,  as 
stated  in  Ethic,  iii.  But  hope  regards  good  things,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XL.,  A.  i).  Therefore  they  have  different  objects 
and  are  not  in  the  same  order.  Therefore  daring  does  not 
ensue  from  hope. 


OF  DARING  501 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  just  as  daring  is  contrary  to  fear,  so  is 
despair  contrary  to  hope.  But  fear  does  not  ensue  from 
despair:  in  fact  despair  excludes  fear,  as  the  Philosopher 
says  [Rhet.  ii.).  Therefore  daring  does  not  result  from 
hope. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  daring  is  intent  on  something  good,  viz., 
victory.  But  it  belongs  to  hope  to  tend  to  that  which  is 
good  and  difficult.  Therefore  daring  is  the  same  as  hope; 
and  consequently  does  not  result  from  it. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.)  tha\ 
those  who  are  hopeful  are  full  of  daring.  Therefore  it  seems 
that  daring  ensues  from  hope. 

/  answer  that,  As  we  have  often  stated  (Q.  XXIL,  A..  2; 
Q.  XXXV.,  A.  i;  Q.  XLL,  A.  i),  all  these  passions  belong 
to  the  appetitive  power.  Now  every  movement  of  the 
appetitive  power  is  reducible  to  one  either  of  pursuit  or  of 
avoidance.  Again,  pursuit  or  avoidance  is  of  something 
either  by  reason  of  itself  or  by  reason  of  something  else. 
By  reason  of  itself,  good  is  the  object  of  pursuit,  and  evil, 
the  object  of  avoidance:  but  by  reason  of  something  else, 
evil  can  be  the  object  of  pursuit,  through  some  good  attach- 
ing to  it;  and  good  can  be  the  object  of  avoidance,  through 
some  evil  attaching  to  it.  Now  that  which  is  by  reason  of 
something  else,  follows  that  which  is  by  reason  of  itself. 
Consequently  pursuit  of  evil  follows  pursuit  of  good;  and 
avoidance  of  good  follows  avoidance  of  evil.  Now  these 
four  things  belong  to  four  passions,  since  pursuit  of  good 
belongs  to  hope,  avoidance  of  evil,  to  fear,  the  pursuit  of 
the  fearful  evil  belongs  to  daring,  and  the  avoidance  of 
good,  to  despair.  It  follows,  therefore,  that  daring  results 
from  hope ;  since  it  is  in  the  hope  of  overcoming  the  threaten- 
ing object  of  fear,  that  one  attacks  it  boldly.  But  despair 
results  from  fear:  since  the  reason  why  a  man  despairs  is 
because  he  fears  the  difficulty  attaching  to  the  good  he  should 
hope  for. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  This  argument  would  hold,  if  good  and  evil 
were  not  co-ordinate  objects.  But  because  evil  has  a  certain 
relation  to  good,  since  it  comes  after  good,  as  privation  comes 


502  QUESTION  XLV 

after  habit;  consequently  daring  which  pursues  evil,  comes 
after  hope  which  pursues  good. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  good,  absolutely  speaking,  is  prior 
to  evil,  yet  the  relation  of  avoidance  to  evil  precedes  its  re- 
lation to  good;  just  as  the  pursuit  of  good  precedes  the 
pursuit  of  evil.  Consequently  just  as  hope  precedes  daring, 
so  fear  precedes  despair.  And  just  as  fear  does  not  always 
lead  to  despair,  but  only  when  it  is  intense;  so  hope  does 
not  always  lead  to  daring,  save  only  when  it  is  strong. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Although  the  object  of  daring  is  an  evil  to 
which,  in  the  estimation  of  the  daring  man,  the  good  of 
victory  is  conjoined;  yet  daring  regards  the  evil,  and  hope 
regards  the  conjoined  good.  In  like  manner  despair  regards 
directly  the  good  which  it  turns  aw^ay  from,  while  fear 
regards  the  conjoined  evil.  Hence,  properly  speaking, 
daring  is  not  a  part  of  hope,  but  its  effect:  just  as  despair  is 
an  effect,  not  a  part,  of  fear.  For  this  reason,  too,  daring 
cannot  be  a  principal  passion. 


Third  Article, 
whether  some  defect  is  a  cause  of  daring  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  some  defect  is  a  cause  of  dm^ng. 
For  the  Philosopher  says  {Problem  xxvii.)  that  lovers  of 
wine  are  strong  and  daring.  But  from  wine  ensues  the  de- 
fect of  drunkenness.     Therefore  daring  is  caused  by  a  defect. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  (Rhet.  ii.)  that  those 
who  have  no  experience  of  danger  are  bold.  But  want  of 
experience  is  a  defect.  Therefore  daring  is  caused  by  a 
defect. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  those  who  have  suffered  wrongs  are  wont 
to  be  daring;  like  the  beasts  when  beaten,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  iii. 
But  the  suffering  of  wTongs  pertains  to  defect.  Therefore 
daring  is  caused  by  a  defect. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.)  that  the 
cause  of  daring  is  the  presence  in  the  imagination  of  the  hope 


OF  DARING  503 

that  the  means  of  safety  are  nigh,  and  that  there  is  nothing  or 
very  little  to  fear.  But  anything  pertaining  to  defect  implies 
either  the  removal  of  the  means  of  safety,  or  the  proximity 
of  something  to  be  feared.  Therefore  nothing  pertaining  to 
defect  is  a  cause  of  daring. 

/  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (AA.  i,  2)  daring  results 
from  hope  and  is  contrary  to  fear:  wherefore  whatever  is 
naturally  apt  to  cause  hope  or  banish  fear,  is  a  cause  of 
daring.  Since,  however,  fear  and  hope,  and  also  daring, 
being  passions,  consist  in  a  movement  of  the  appetite,  and 
in  a  certain  bodily  transmutation ;  a  thing  may  be  considered 
as  the  cause  of  daring  in  two  ways,  whether  by  raising  hope, 
or  by  banishing  of  fear ;  in  one  way,  on  the  part  of  the  appe- 
titive movement ;  in  another  way,  on  the  part  of  the  bodily 
transmutation. 

On  the  part  of  the  appetitive  movement  which  follows 
apprehension,  hope  that  leads  to  daring  is  roused  by  those 
things  that  make  us  reckon  victory  as  possible.  Such 
things  regard  either  our  owm  power,  as  bodily  strength,  ex- 
perience of  dangers,  abundance  of  wealth,  and  the  like;  or 
they  regard  the  power  of  others,  such  as  having  a  great 
number  of  friends  or  of  any  other  means  of  help,  especially, 
if  a  man  trust  in  the  Divine  assistance;  wherefore  those  are 
more  daring,  with  whom  it  is  well  in  regard  to  godlike  things 
[Rhet.  ii.).  Fear  is  banished,  in  this  way,  by  the  removal  of 
threatening  causes  of  fear;  for  instance,  by  the  fact  that  a 
man  has  no  enemies,  through  having  harmed  nobody,  so 
that  he  is  not  aware  of  any  imminent  danger;  since  those 
especially  appear  to  be  threatened  by  danger,  who  have 
harmed  others. 

On  the  part  of  the  bodily  transmutation,  daring  is  caused 
through  the  incitement  of  hope  and  the  banishment  of  fear, 
by  those  things  which  raise  the  temperature  about  the  heart. 
Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  [De  Part.  Animal,  iii.)  that 
those  whose  heart  is  small  in  size,  are  more  daring ;  while 
animals  whose  heart  is  large  are  timid  ;  because  the  natural 
heat  is  unable  to  give  the  same  degree  of  temperature  to  a  large 
as  to  a  small  heart ;  just  as  a  fire  does  not  heat  a  large  house 


504  QUESTION  XLV 

as  well  as  it  does  a  small  house.  He  says  also  [Problem  xxvii.) 
that  those  whose  lungs  contain  much  blood,  are  more  daring, 
through  the  heat  in  the  heart  that  results  therefrom.  He  says 
also  in  the  same  passage  that  lovers  of  wine  are  more  daring, 
on  account  of  the  heat  of  the  wine :  hence  it  has  been  said 
above  (Q.  XL.,  A.  6)  that  drunkenness  conduces  to  hope, 
since  the  heat  in  the  heart  banishes  fear  and  raises  hope, 
by  reason  of  the  dilatation  and  enlargement  of  the 
he-art. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Drunkenness  causes  daring,  not  through 
being  a  defect,  but  through  dilating  the  heart:  and  again 
through  making  a  man  think  greatly  of  himself. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Those  who  have  no  experience  of  dangers, 
are  more  daring,  not  on  account  of  a  defect,  but  accidentally, 
i.e.,  in  so  far  as  through  being  inexperienced  they  do  not 
know  their  own  faihngs,  nor  the  dangers  that  threaten. 
Hence  it  is  that  the  removal  of  the  cause  of  fear  gives  rise 
to  daring. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  the  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.)  those  w>ho 
have  been  wronged  are  courageous,  because  they  think  that  God 
comes  to  the  assistance  of  those  who  suffer  unjustly. 

Hence  it  is  evident  that  no  defect  causes  daring  except 
accidentally,  i.e.,  in  so  far  as  some  excellence  attaches  thereto, 
real  or  imaginary,  either  in  oneself  or  in  another. 

Fourth  Article. 

whether  the  brave  are  more  eager  at  first  than  in 

the  midst  of  danger  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  brave  are  more  eager  at 
first  than  in  the  midst  of  danger.  Because  trembling  is 
caused  by  fear,  which  is  contrary  to  daring,  as  stated  above 
(A.  I.;  Q.  XLIV.,  A.  3).  But  the  brave  sometimes  tremble 
at  first,  as  the  Philosopher  says  {Problem  xxvii.).  There- 
fore they  are  not  more  eager  at  first  than  in  the  midst  of 
danger. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  passion  is  intensified  by  an  increase  in 


OF  DARING  505 

its  object:  thus  since  a  good  is  lovable,  what  is  better  is  yet 
more  lovable.  But  the  object  of  daring  is  something  diffi- 
cult. Therefore  the  greater  the  difficulty,  the  greater  the 
daring.  But  danger  is  more  arduous  and  difficult  when 
present.     It  is  then  therefore  that  daring  is  greatest. 

Obj.  3  Further,  anger  is  provoked  by  the  infliction  of 
wounds.  But  anger  causes  daring;  for  the  Philosopher  says 
{Rhet.  ii.)  that  anger  makes  man  hold.  Therefore  when  man 
is  in  the  midst  of  danger  and  when  he  is  being  beaten,  then 
is  he  most  daring. 

On  the  contrary,  It  is  said  in  Ethic,  iii.  that  the  daring  are 
precipitate  and  full  of  eagerness  before  the  danger,  yet  in  the 
midst  of  dangers  they  stand  aloof. 

I  answer  that,  Daring,  being  a  movement  of  the  sensitive 
appetite,  follows  an  apprehension  of  the  sensitive  faculty. 
But  the  sensitive  faculty  cannot  make  comparisons,  nor  can 
it  inquire  into  circumstances;  its  judgment  is  instantaneous. 
Now  it  happens  sometimes  that  it  is  impossible  for  a  man 
to  take  note  in  an  instant  of  all  the  difficulties  of  a  certain 
situation:  hence  there  arises  the  movement  of  daring  to 
face  the  danger;  so  that  when  he  comes  to  experience  the 
danger,  he  feels  the  difficulty  to  be  greater  than  he  expected, 
and  so  gives  way. 

On  the  other  hand,  reason  discusses  all  the  difficulties  of 
a  situation.  Consequently  men  of  fortitude  who  face 
danger  according  to  the  judgment  of  reason,  at  first  seem 
slack,  because  they  face  the  danger  not  from  passion  but  with 
due  deliberation.  Yet  when  they  are  in  the  midst  of  danger, 
they  experience  nothing  unforeseen,  but  sometimes  the 
difficulty  turns  out  to  be  less  than  they  anticipated;  where- 
fore they  are  more  persevering. — Moreover,  it  may  be  be- 
cause they  face  the  danger  on  account  of  the  good  of  virtue 
which  is  the  abiding  object  of  their  will,  however  great  the 
danger  may  prove:  whereas  men  of  daring  face  the  danger 
on  account  of  a  mere  thought  giving  rise  to  hope  and  banish- 
ing fear,  as  stated  above  (A.  3). 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Trembling  does  occur  in  men  of  daring,  on 
account  of  the  heat  being  withdrawn  from  the  outer  to  the 


5o6  QUESTION  XLV 

inner  parts  of  the  body,  as  occurs  also  in  those  who  are 
afraid.  But  in  men  of  daring  the  heat  withdraws  to  the 
heart;  whereas  in  those  who  are  afraid,  it  withdraws  to  the 
inferior  parts  [cf.  A.  i;  A.  3  ad  3). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  The  object  of  love  is  good  simply,  wherefore 
if  it  be  increased,  love  is  increased  simply.  But  the  object 
of  daring  is  a  compound  of  good  and  evil ;  and  the  movement 
of  daring  towards  evil  presupposes  the  movement  of  hope 
towards  good.  If,  therefore,  so  much  difficulty  be  added 
to  the  danger  that  it  overcomes  hope,  the  movement  of 
daring  does  not  ensue,  but  fails. — But  if  the  movement  of 
daring  does  ensue,  the  greater  the  danger,  the  greater  is  the 
daring  considered  to  be. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Hurt  does  not  give  rise  to  anger  unless  there 
be  some  kind  of  hope,  as  we  shall  see  later  on  (Q.  XLVI., 
A.  i).  Consequently  if  the  danger  be  so  great  as  to  banish 
all  hope  of  victory,  anger  does  not  ensue. — -It  is  true,  how- 
ever, that  if  anger  does  ensue,  there  will  be  greater  daring. 


QUESTION  XLVI. 

OF  ANGER,  IN  ITSELF. 

{In  Eight  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  anger;  and  (i)  anger  in  itself:  (2)  the 
cause  that  produces  anger :  (3)  the  effect  of  anger. 

Under  the  first  head  there  are  eight  points  of  inquiry: 
(i)  Whether  anger  is  a  special  passion  ?  (2)  Whether  the 
object  of  anger  is  good  or  evil  ?  (3)  Whether  anger  is  in 
the  concupiscible  faculty  ?  (4)  Whether  anger  is  accom- 
panied by  an  act  of  reason  ?  (5)  Whether  anger  is  more 
natural  than  desire  ?  (6)  W^hether  anger  is  more  grievous 
than  hatred  ?  (7)  Whether  anger  is  only  towards  those 
with  whom  we  have  a  relation  of  justice  ?  (8)  Of  the 
species  of  anger. 

First  Article, 
whether  anger  is  a  special  passion  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  anger  is  not  a  special  passion. 
For  the  irascible  power  takes  its  name  from  anger  [ira). 
But  there  are  several  passions  in  this  power,  not  only  one. 
Therefore  anger  is  not  a  special  passion. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  to  every  special  passion  there  is  a  con- 
trary passion;  as  is  evident  by  going  through  them  one  by 
one.  But  no  passion  is  contrary  to  anger,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXIII.,  A.  3).     Therefore  anger  is  not  a  special  passion. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  one  special  passion  does  not  include 
another.  But  anger  includes  several  passions:  since  it 
accompanies  sorrow,  pleasure,  and  hope,  as  the  Philosopher 
states  {Rhet.  ii.).     Therefore  anger  is  not  a  special  passion. 

507 


5o8  QUESTION  XLVI 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene   (De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)   calls 
anger  a  special  passion:  and  so  does  Tully  (QucBst.  Tusc.  iv.). 

/  answer  that,  A  thing  is  said  to  be  general  in  two  ways. 
First,  by  predication  ;  thus  animal  is  general  in  respect  of 
all  animals. — Secondly,  by  causality;  thus  the  sun  is  the 
general  cause  of  all  things  generated  here  below,  according 
to  Dionysius  [Div.  Nom.  iv.).  Because  just  as  a  genus 
contains  potentially  many  differences,  according  to  a  like- 
ness of  matter;  so  an  efficient  cause  contains  many  effects 
according  to  its  active  power. — Now  it  happens  that  an 
effect  is  produced  by  the  concurrence  of  various  causes; 
and  since  every  cause  remains  somewhat  in  its  effect,  we 
may  say  that,  in  yet  a  third  way,  an  effect  which  is  due  to 
the  concurrence  of  several  causes,  has  a  certain  generality, 
inasmuch  as  several  causes  are,  in  a  fashion,  actually  existing 
therein. 

Accordingly  in  the  first  way,  anger  is  not  a  general  passion, 
but  is  condivided  with  the  other  passions,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXIII. ,  A.  4). — In  like  manner,  neither  is  it  in  the  second 
way:  since  it  is  not  a  cause  of  the  other  passions.  But  in 
this  way  love  may  be  called  a  general  passion,  as  Augustine 
declares  {De  Civ.  Dei.  xiv.),  because  love  is  the  primary  root 
of  all  the  other  passions,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXVI I. ,  A.  4). 
— But,  in  the  third  way,  anger  may  be  called  a  general  pas- 
sion, inasmuch  as  it  is  caused  by  a  concurrence  of  several 
passions.  Because  the  movement  of  anger  does  not  arise 
save  on  account  of  some  pain  inflicted,  and  unless  there  be 
desire  and  hope  of  revenge:  for,  as  the  Philosopher  says 
(Rhet.  ii.),  the  angry  man  hopes  to  punish  ;  since  he  craves  for 
revenge  as  being  possible.  Consequently  if  the  person,  who 
inflicted  the  injury,  excel  very  much,  anger  does  not  ensue, 
but  only  sorrow,  as  Avicenna  states  (De  Anima  iv.). 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  irascible  power  takes  its  name  from  ira 
(anger),  not  because  every  movement  of  that  power  is  one 
of  anger ;  but  because  all  its  movements  terminate  in  anger ; 
and  because,  of  all  these  movements,  anger  is  the  most 
patent. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  From  the  very  fact  that  anger  is  caused  by 


OF  ANGER,  IN  ITSELF  509 

contrary  passions,  i.e.,  by  hope,  which  is  of  good,  and  by 
sorrow,  which  is  of  evil,  it  includes  in  itself  contrariety :  and 
consequently  it  has  no  contrary  outside  itself.  Thus  also 
in  mixed  colours  there  is  no  contrariety,  except  that  of  the 
simple  colours  from  which  they  are  made. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Anger  includes  several  passions,  not  indeed 
as  a  genus  includes  several  species;  but  rather  according  to 
the  inclusion  of  cause  and  effect. 


Second  Article, 
whether  the  object  of  anger  is  good  or  evil  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  object  of  anger  is  evil.  For 
Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius,  De  Nat.  Horn,  xxi.)  sa^^s  that 
anger  is  the  sword-bearer  of  desire,  inasmuch,  to  wit,  as  it 
assails  whatever  obstacle  stands  in  the  way  of  desire.  But 
an  obstacle  has  the  character  of  evil.  Therefore  anger 
regards  evil  as  its  object. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  anger  and  hatred  agree  in  their  effect, 
since  each  seeks  to  inflict  harm  on  another.  But  hatred 
regards  evil  as  its  object,  as  stated,  above  (Q.  XXIX.,  A.  i). 
Therefore  anger  does  also. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  anger  arises  from  sorrow;  wherefore  the 
Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vii.)  that  anger  acts  with  sorrow. 
But  evil  is  the  object  of  sorrow.  Therefore  it  is  also  the 
object  of  anger. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine  says  {Conf.  ii.)  that  anger  craves 
for  revenge.     But  the  desire  for  revenge  is  a  desire  for  some- 
thing good:  since  revenge  belongs  to  justice.     Therefore  the 
object  of  anger  is  good. 

2.  Moreover,  anger  is  always  accompanied  by  hope,  where- 
fore it  causes  pleasure,  as  the  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.). 
But  the  object  of  hope  and  of  pleasure  is  good.  Therefore 
good  is  also  the  object  of  anger. 

I  answer  that,  The  movement  of  the  appetitive  power 
follows  an  act  of  the  apprehensive  power.  Now  the  appre- 
hensive power  apprehends  a  thing  in  two  ways.     First,  by 


510  QUESTION  XLVI 

way  of  an  incomplex  object,  as  when  we  understand  what  a 
man  is;  secondly,  by  way  of  a  complex  object,  as  when  we 
understand  that  whiteness  is  in  a  man.  Consequently  in 
each  of  these  ways  the  appetitive  power  can  tend  to  both 
good  and  evil: — by  way  of  a  simple  and  incomplex  object, 
when  the  appetite  simply  follows  and  adheres  to  good,  or 
recoils  from  evil:  and  such  movements  are  desire,  hope, 
pleasure,  sorrow,  and  so  forth : — by  way  of  a  complex  object, 
w^hen  the  appetite  tends  to  the  effect  of  some  good  or  evil 
being  in,  or  being  done  to  another,  the  appetite  either  tend- 
ing towards  some  particular  object,  or  recoiling  from  some 
other.  This  is  evident  in  the  case  of  love  and  hatred:  for 
we  love  someone,  in  so  far  as  we  wish  him  some  good;  and 
we  hate  someone,  in  so  far  as  we  wish  him  some  evil.  It  is 
the  same  with  anger ;  for  when  a  man  is  angry,  he  wishes  to 
be  avenged  on  someone.  Hence  the  movement  of  anger  has  a 
twofold  tendency:  viz.,  to  vengeance  itself,  which  it  desires 
and  hopes  for  as  being  a  good,  wherefore  it  takes  pleasure  in 
it;  and  to  the  person  on  whom  it  seeks  vengeance,  as  to 
something  contrary  and  hurtful,  which  bears  the  character 
of  evil. 

We  must,  however,  observe  a  twofold  difference  in  this 
respect,  between  anger  on  the  one  side,  and  hatred  and  love 
on  the  other.  The  first  difference  is  that  anger  always  re- 
gards two  objects :  whereas  love  and  hatred  sometimes  regard 
but  one  object,  as  when  a  man  is  said  to  love  wine  or  some- 
thing of  the  kind,  or  to  hate  it.^The  second  difference  is, 
that  both  the  objects  of  love  are  good:  since  the  lover  wishes 
good  to  someone,  as  to  something  agreeable  to  himself: 
while  both  the  objects  of  hatred  bear  the  character  of  evil: 
for  the  man  who  hates,  wishes  evil  to  someone,  as  to  some- 
thing disagreeable  to  him.  Whereas  anger  regards  one  ob- 
ject under  the  aspect  of  good,  viz.,  vengeance,  which  it  de- 
sires to  have;  and  the  other  object  under  the  aspect  of  evil, 
viz.,  the  noxious  person,  on  whom  it  seeks  to  be  avenged. 
Consequently  it  is  a  passion  somewhat  made  up  of  contrary 
passions. 

This  suffices  for  the  Replies  to  the  Objections. 


OF  ANGER,  IN  ITSELF  511 

Third  Article, 
whether  anger  is  in  the  concupiscible  faculty  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  anger  is  in  the  concupiscible 
faculty.  For  TuUy  says  [QiicBst.  Tusc.  iv.)  that  anger  is  a 
kind  of  desire.  But  desire  is  in  the  concupiscible  faculty. 
Therefore  anger  is  too. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Augustine  says  in  his  Rule,  that  anger 
grows  into  hatred :  and  Tully  says  {loc.  cit.)  that  hatred  is 
inveterate  anger.  But  hatred,  like  love,  is  a  concupiscible 
passion.     Therefore  anger  is  in  the  concupiscible  faculty. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Damascene  {De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.)  and 
Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius,  De  Nat.  Horn,  xxi.)  say  that 
anger  is  made  up  of  sorrow  and  desire.  Both  of  these  are  in 
the  concupiscible  faculty.  Therefore  anger  is  a  concupiscible 
passion. 

On  the  contrary,  The  concupiscible  is  distinct  from  the 
irascible  faculty.  If,  therefore,  anger  were  in  the  con- 
cupiscible power,  the  irascible  would  not  take  its  name 
from  it. 

/  answer  that.  As  stated  above  (Q.  XXIIL,  K.  i),  the 
passions  of  the  irascible  part  differ  from  the  passions  of  the 
concupiscible  faculty,  in  that  the  objects  of  the  concupiscible 
passions  are  good  and  evil  absolutely  considered,  whereas 
the  objects  of  the  irascible  passions  are  good  and  evil  of  a 
certain  elevation  or  arduousness.  Now  it  has  been  stated 
(A.  2)  that  anger  regards  two  objects:  viz.,  the  vengeance 
that  it  seeks;  and  the  person  on  whom  it  seeks  vengeance; 
and  in  respect  of  both,  anger  requires  a  certain  arduousness : 
for  the  movement  of  anger  does  not  arise,  unless  there  be 
some  magnitude  about  both  these  objects;  since  we  make 
no  ado  about  things  that  are  naught  or  very  minute,  as  the 
Philosopher  observes  {Rhet.  ii.).  It  is  therefore  evident 
that  anger  is  not  in  the  concupiscible,  but  in  the  irascible 
faculty. 

Reply  Obj,  i.  Tully  gives  the  name  of  desire  to  any  kind 


512  QUESTION  XLVI 

of  craving  for  a  future  good,  without  discriminating  between 
that  which  is  arduous  and  that  which  is  not.  Accordingly 
he  reckons  anger  as  a  kind  of  desire,  inasmuch  as  it  is  a  desire 
of  vengeance.  In  this  sense,  however,  desire  is  common  to 
the  irascible  and  concupiscible  faculties. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Anger  is  said  to  grow  into  hatred,  not  as 
though  the  same  passion  which  at  first  was  anger,  after- 
wards becomes  hatred  by  becoming  inveterate;  but  by  a 
process  of  causality.  For  anger  when  it  lasts  a  long  time 
engenders  hatred. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  Anger  is  said  to  be  composed  of  sorrow  and 
desire,  not  as  though  they  were  its  parts,  but  because  they  are 
its  causes:  and  it  has  been  said  above  (Q.  XXV.,  A.  2)  that 
the  concupiscible  passions  are  the  causes  of  the  irascible 
passions. 

Fourth  Article, 
whether  anger  requires  an  act  of  reason  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  anger  does  not  require  an  act 
of  reason.  For,  since  anger  is  a  passion,  it  is  in  the  sensitive 
appetite.  But  the  sensitive  appetite  follows  an  apprehension, 
not  of  reason,  but  of  the  sensitive  faculty.  Therefore  anger 
does  not  require  an  act  of  reason. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  dumb  animals  are  devoid  of  reason:  and 
yet  they  are  seen  to  be  angry.  Therefore  anger  does  not 
require  an  act  of  reason. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  drunkenness  fetters  the  reason:  whereas 
it  is  conducive  to  anger.  Therefore  anger  does  not  require 
an  act  of  reason. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  vii.)  that 
anger  listens  to  reason  somewhat. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  2),  anger  is  a  desire  for 
vengeance.  Now  vengeance  implies  a  comparison  between 
the  punishment  to  be  inflicted  and  the  hurt  done;  wherefore 
the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  vii.)  that  anger,  as  if  it  had 
drawn  the  inference  that  it  ought  to  quarrel  with  such  a  person, 
is  therefore  immediately  exasperated.     Now  to  compare  and 


OF  ANGER,  IN  ITSELF  513 

to  draw  an  inference  is  an  act  of  reason.  Therefore  anger, 
in  a  fashion,  requires  an  act  of  reason. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  movement  of  the  appetitive  power  may 
follow  an  act  of  reason  in  two  ways.  In  the  first  way,  it 
f oUows  the  reason  in  so  far  as  the  reason  commands :  and  thus 
the  will  follows  reason,  wherefore  it  is  called  the  rational 
appetite.  In  another  way,  it  follows  reason  in  so  far  as  the 
reason  denounces,  and  thus  anger  follows  reason.  For  the 
Philosopher  says  {Problem  xxviii.)  that  anger  follows  reason, 
not  in  obedience  to  reason's  command,  but  as  a  result  of  reason  s 
denouncing  the  injury.  Because  the  sensitive  appetite  is 
subject  to  the  reason,  not  immediately  but  through  the 
will. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Dumb  animals  have  a  natural  instinct  im- 
parted to  them  by  the  Divine  Reason,  in  virtue  of  which 
they  are  gifted  with  movements,  both  internal  and  external, 
like  unto  rational  movements,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XL.,  A.  3). 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  in  Ethic,  vii.,  anger  listens  somewhat 
to  reason  in  so  far  as  reason  denounces  the  injury  inflicted, 
but  listens  not  perfectly,  because  it  does  not  observe  the  rule 
of  reason  as  to  the  measure  of  vengeance.  Anger,  therefore, 
requires  an  act  of  reason;  and  yet  proves  a  hindrance  to 
reason.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  {Problem  iii.)  that 
those  who  are  very  drunk,  so  as  to  be  incapable  of  the  use 
of  reason,  do  not  get  angry :  but  those  who  are  slightly  drunk, 
do  get  angry,  through  being  still  able,  though  hampered,  to 
form  a  judgment  of  reason. 

Fifth  Article, 
whether  anger  is  more  natural  than  desire  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fifth  Article.: — ■ 

Objection  1.  It  seems  that  anger  is  not  more  natural  than 
desire.  Because  it  is  proper  to  man  to  be  by  nature  a  gentle 
animal.  But  gentleness  is  contrary  to  anger,  as  the  Philos- 
opher states  {Rhet.  ii.).  Therefore  anger  is  not  more  natural 
than  desire,  in  fact  it  seems  to  be  altogether  unnatural 
to  man. 

II-  I  33 


514  QUESTION  XLVI 

Obj.  2.  Further,  reason  is  contrasted  with  nature:  since 
those  things  that  are  according  to  reason,  are  not  said  to 
act  according  to  nature.  Now  anger  requires  an  act  of 
reason,  but  desire  does  not,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  vii.  Therefore 
desire  is  more  natural  than  anger. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  anger  is  a  craving  for  vengeance:  while 
desire  is  a  craving  for  those  things  especially  which  are 
pleasant  to  the  touch,  viz.,  for  pleasures  of  the  table  and  for 
sexual  pleasures.  But  these  things  are  more  natural  to  man 
than  vengeance.   Therefore  desire  is  more  natural  than  anger. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  vii.)  that 
anger  is  more  natural  than  desire. 

I  answer  that.  By  natural  we  mean  that  which  is  caused 
by  nature,  as  stated  in  Phys.  ii.  Consequently  the  question 
as  to  whether  a  particular  passion  is  more  or  less  natural 
cannot  be  decided  without  reference  to  the  cause  of  that 
passion.  Now  the  cause  of  a  passion,  as  stated  above 
(Q.  XXX VL,  A.  2),  may  be  considered  in  two  ways:  first, 
on  the  part  of  the  object;  secondly,  on  the  part  of  the  sub- 
ject. If  then  we  consider  the  cause  of  anger  and  of  desire, 
on  the  part  of  the  object,  thus  desire,  especially  of  pleasures 
of  the  table,  and  of  sexual  pleasures,  is  more  natural  than 
anger;  in  so  far  as  these  pleasures  are  more  natural  to  man 
than  vengeance. 

If,  however,  w^e  consider  the  cause  of  anger  on  the  part 
of  the  subject,  thus  anger,  in  a  manner,  is  more  natural; 
and,  in  a  manner,  desire  is  more  natural.  Because  the 
nature  of  an  individual  man  may  be  considered  either  as  to 
the  generic,  or  as  to  the  specific  nature,  or  again  as  to  the 
particular  temperament  of  the  individual.  If  then  we  con- 
sider the  generic  nature,  i.e.,  the  nature  of  this  man  con- 
sidered as  an  animal ;  thus  desire  is  more  natural  than  anger ; 
because  it  is  from  this  very  generic  nature  that  man  is  in- 
clined to  desire  those  things  which  tend  to  preserve  in  him 
the  life  both  of  the  species  and  of  the  individual. — If,  how- 
ever, we  consider  the  specific  nature,  i.e.,  the  nature  of  this 
man  as  a  rational  being ;  then  anger  is  more  natural  to  man 
than  desire,  in  so  far  as  anger  follows  reason  more  than 


OF  ANGER,  IN  ITSELF  515 

desire  does.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.) 
that  reve7ige  which  pertains  to  anger  is  more  natural  to  man 
than  meekness  :  for  it  is  natural  to  everything  to  rise  up 
against  things  contrary  and  hurtful. — And  if  we  consider 
the  nature  of  the  individual,  in  respect  of  his  particular 
temperament,  thus  anger  is  more  natural  than  desire;  for 
the  reason  that  anger  is  prone  to  ensue  from  the  natural 
tendency  to  anger,  more  than  desire,  or  any  other  passion, 
is  to  ensue  from  a  natural  tendency  to  desire,  which  ten- 
dencies result  from  a  man's  individual  temperament.  Be- 
cause disposition  to  anger  is  due  to  a  bilious  temperament; 
and  of  all  the  humours,  the  bile  moves  quickest ;  for  it  is  like 
fire.  Consequently  he  that  is  temperamentally  disposed 
to  anger  is  sooner  incensed  with  anger,  than  he  that  is 
temperamentally  disposed  to  desire,  is  inflamed  with  desire : 
and  for  this  reason  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  vii.)  that  a 
disposition  to  anger  is  more  liable  to  be  traUvSmitted  from 
parent  to  child,  than  a  disposition  to  desire. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  We  may  consider  in  man  both  the  natural 
temperament  on  the  part  of  the  body,  and  the  reason.  On 
the  part  of  the  bodily  temperament,  a  man,  considered 
specifically,  does  not  naturally  excel  others  either  in  anger 
or  in  any  other  passion,  on  account  of  the  moderation  of  his 
temperament.  But  other  animals,  for  as  much  as  their 
temperament  recedes  from  this  moderation  and  approaches 
to  an  extreme  disposition,  are  naturally  disposed  to  some 
excess  of  passion,  such  as  the  lion  in  daring,  the  hound  in 
anger,  the  hare  in  fear,  and  so  forth. — On  the  part  of  reason, 
however,  it  is  natural  to  man,  both  to  be  angry  and  to  be 
gentle:  in  so  far  as  reason  somewhat  causes  anger,  by  de- 
nouncing the  injury  which  causes  anger;  and  somewhat 
appeases  anger,  in  so  far  as  the  angry  man  does  not  listen 
perfectly  to  the  command  of  reason,  as  stated  above  {A.  ^ad-^). 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Reason  itself  belongs  to  the  nature  of  man: 
wherefore  from  the  very  fact  that  anger  requires  an  act  of 
reason,  it  follows  that  it  is,  in  a  manner,  natural  to  man. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  This  argument  regards  anger  and  desire  on 
the  part  of  the  object. 


5i6  QUESTION  XLVI 


Sixth  Article, 
whether  anger  is  more  grievous  than  hatred  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Sixth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  anger  is  more  grievous  than 
hatred.  For  it  is  written  (Pro v.  xxvii.  4)  that  anger  hath  no 
mercy,  nor  fury  when  it  hreaketh  forth.  But  hatred  some- 
times has  mercy.  Therefore  anger  is  more  grievous  than 
hatred. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  it  is  worse  to  suffer  evil  and  to  grieve  for 
it,  than  merely  to  suffer  it.  But  when  a  man  hates,  he  is 
contented  if  the  object  of  his  hatred  suffer  evil:  whereas  the 
angry  man  is  not  satisfied  unless  the  object  of  his  anger 
know  it  and  be  aggrieved  thereby,  as  the  Philosopher  says 
{Rhet.  ii.).     Therefore,  anger  is  more  grievous  than  hatred. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  a  thing  seems  to  be  so  much  the  more 
firm  according  as  more  things  concur  to  set  it  up:  thus  a 
habit  is  all  the  more  settled  through  being  caused  by 
several  acts.  But  anger  is  caused  by  the  concurrence  of 
several  passions,  as  stated  above  (A.  i) :  whereas  hatred  is 
not.  Therefore  anger  is  more  settled  and  more  grievous 
than  hatred. 

On  the  contrary,  Augustine,  in  his  Rule,  compares  hatred 
to  a  beam,  but  anger  to  a  mote. 

I  answer  that.  The  species  and  nature  of  a  passion  are  taken 
from  its  object.  Now  the  object  of  anger  is  the  same  in 
substance  as  the  object  of  hatred;  since,  just  as  the  hater 
wishes  evil  to  him  whom  he  hates,  so  does  the  angry  man 
wish  evil  to  him  with  whom  he  is  angry.  But  there  is  a 
difference  of  aspect :  for  the  hater  desires  evil  to  his  enemy, 
as  evil,  whereas  the  angry  man  wishes  evil  to  him  with  whom 
he  is  angry,  not  as  evil  but  in  so  far  as  it  has  an  aspect  of 
good,  that  is,  in  so  far  as  he  reckons  it  as  just,  since  it  is  a 
means  of  vengeance.  Wherefore  also  it  has  been  said  above 
(A.  2)  that  hatred  implies  application  of  evil  to  evil,  whereas 
anger  denotes  application  of  good  to  evil. — Now  it  is  evident 
that  to  seek  evil  under  the  aspect  of  justice,  is  a  lesser  evil, 


OF  ANGER,  IN  ITSELF  517 

than  simply  to  seek  evil  to  someone.  Because  to  wish  evil 
to  someone  under  the  aspect  of  justice,  may  be  according 
to  the  virtue  of  justice,  if  it  be  in  conformity  with  the  order 
of  reason ;  and  anger  fails  only  in  this,  that  it  does  not  obey 
the  precept  of  reason  in  taking  vengeance.  Consequently 
it  is  evident  that  hatred  is  far  worse  and  graver  than  anger. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  In  anger  and  hatred  two  points  may  be 
considered:  namely,  the  thing  desired,  and  the  intensity  of 
the  desire.  As  to  the  thing  desired,  anger  has  more  mercy 
than  hatred  has.  For  since  hatred  desires  another's  evil 
for  evil's  sake,  it  is  satisfied  with  no  particular  measure  of 
evil:  because  those  things  that  are  desired  for  their  own  sake, 
are  desired  without  measure,  as  the  Philosopher  states 
(Polit.  i.),  instancing  a  miser  with  regard  to  riches.  Hence 
it  is  written  (Ecclus.  xii.  16) :  An  enemy  .  .  .  if  he  find  an  op- 
portunity, will  not  he  satisfied  with  blood. — Anger,  on  the  other 
hand,  seeks  evil  only  under  the  aspect  of  a  just  means  of 
vengeance.  Consequently  when  the  evil  inflicted  goes 
beyond  the  measure  of  justice  according  to  the  estimate  of 
the  angry  man,  then  he  has  mercy.  Wherefore  the  Phil- 
osopher says  {Rhet.  ii.)  that  the  angry  man  is  appeased  if 
many  evils  befall,  whereas  the  hater  is  never  appeased. 

As  to  the  intensity  of  the  desire,  anger  excludes  mercy 
more  than  hatred  does;  because  the  movement  of  anger  is 
more  impetuous,  through  the  heating  of  the  bile.  Hence 
the  passage  quoted  continues:  Who  can  bear  the  violence  of 
one  provoked  ? 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  stated  above,  an  angry  man  desires  evil 
to  someone,  in  so  far  as  this  evil  is  a  means  of  just  vengeance. 
Now  vengeance  is  wrought  by  the  infliction  of  a  punishment : 
and  the  nature  of  punishment  consists  in  being  contrary 
to  the  will,  painful,  and  inflicted  for  some  fault.  Conse- 
quently an  angry  man  desires  this, — that  the  person  whom 
he  is  hurting,  may  feel  it  and  be  in  pain,  and  know  that  this 
has  befallen  him  on  account  of  the  harm  he  has  done  the 
other.  The  hater,  on  the  other  hand,  cares  not  for  all  this, 
since  he  desires  another's  evil  as  such. — It  is  not  true,  how- 
ever, that  an  evil  is  worse  through  giving  pain:  because 


5i8  QUESTION  XLVI 

injustice  and  imprudence,  although  evil,  yet,  being  voluntary, 
do  not  grieve  those  in  whom  they  are,  as  the  Philosopher 
observes  {Rhet.  ii.). 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  That  which  proceeds  from  several  causes, 
is  more  settled  when  these  causes  are  of  one  kind :  but  it  may 
be  that  one  cause  prevails  over  many  others.  Now  hatred 
ensues  from  a  more  lasting  cause  than  anger  does.  Because 
anger  arises  from  an  emotion  of  the  soul  due  to  the  wrong 
inflicted;  whereas  hatred  ensues  from  a  disposition  in  a 
man,  by  reason  of  which  he  considers  that  which  he  hates 
to  be  contrary  and  hurtful  to  him.  Consequently,  as 
passion  is  more  transitory  than  disposition  or  habit,  so 
anger  is  less  lasting  than  hatred;  although  hatred  itself  is 
a  passion  ensuing  from  this  disposition.  Hence  the 
Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.)  that  hatred  is  more  incurable 
than  anger. 

Seventh  Article. 

whether  anger  is  only  towards  those  to  whom 
-  one  has  an  obligation  of  justice  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Seventh  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  anger  is  not  only  towards  those 
to  whom  one  has  an  obligation  of  justice.  For  there  is  no 
justice  between  man  and  irrational  beings.  And  yet  some- 
times one  is  angry  with  irrational  beings ;  thus,  out  of  anger, 
a  writer  throws  away  his  pen,  or  a  rider  strikes  his  horse. 
Therefore  anger  is  not  only  towards  those  to  whom  one  has 
an  obligation  of  justice. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  there  is  no  justice  towards  oneself  .  .  .  nor 
is  there  justice  towards  one's  own  {Ethic,  v.).  But  sometimes 
a  man  is  angry  with  himself;  for  instance,  a  penitent,  on 
account  of  his  sin;  hence  it  is  written  (Ps.  iv.  5) :  Be  ye  angry 
and  sin  not.  Therefore  anger  is  not  only  towards  those 
with  whom  one  has  a  relation  of  justice. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  justice  and  injustice  can  be  of  one  man 
towards  an  entire  class,  or  a  whole  community:  for  instance, 
when  the  state  injures  an  individual.  But  anger  is  not 
towards  a  class  but  only  towards  an  individual,   as  the 


OF  ANGER,  IN  ITSELF  519 

Philosopher  states  [Rhet.  ii.)-  Therefore  properly  speaking, 
anger  is  not  towards  those  with  whom  one  is  in  relation 
of  justice  or  injustice. 

The  contrary,  however,  may  be  gathered  from  the  Philoso- 
pher {Rhet.  ii.). 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  6),  anger  desires  evil 
as  being  a  means  of  just  vengeance.  Consequently,  anger 
is  towards  those  to  whom  we  are  just  or  unjust:  since 
vengeance  is  an  act  of  justice,  and  wrong-doing  is  an  act  of 
injustice.  Therefore  both  on  the  part  of  the  cause,  viz.,  the 
harm  done  by  another,  and  on  the  part  of  the  vengeance 
sought  by  the  angry  man,  it  is  evident  that  anger  concerns 
those  to  whom  one  is  just  or  unjust. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  As  stated  above  (A.  ^ad2),  anger,  though  it 
follows  an  act  of  reason,  can  nevertheless  be  in  dumb  animals 
that  are  devoid  of  reason,  in  so  far  as  through  their  natural 
instinct  they  are  moved  by  their  imagination  to  something 
like  rational  action.  Since  then  in  man  there  is  both  reason 
and  imagination,  the  movement  of  anger  can  be  aroused  in 
man  in  two  ways.  First,  when  only  his  imagination 
denounces  the  injury:  and,  in  this  way,  man  is  aroused  to 
a  movement  of  anger  even  against  irrational  and  inanimate 
beings,  which  movement  is  like  that  which  occurs  in  animals 
against  anything  that  injures  them. — Secondly,  by  the 
reason  denouncing  the  injury:  and  thus,  according  to  the 
Philosopher  [Rhet.  ii.),  it  is  impossible  to  he  angry  with  in- 
sensible things,  or  with  the  dead :  both  because  they  feel  no 
pain,  which  is,  above  all,  what  the  angry  man  seeks  in  those 
with  whom  he  is  angry :  an,d  because  one  cannot  be  avenged 
on  them,  since  they  can  do  us  no  harm. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  As  the  Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  v.),  meta- 
phorically speaking  there  is  a  certain  justice  and  injustice 
between  a  man  and  himself,  in  so  far  as  the  reason  rules  the 
irascible  and  concupiscible  parts  of  the  soul .  And  in  this  sense 
a  man  is  said  to  be  avenged  on  himself,  and,  consequently, 
to  be  angry  with  himself.  But  properly,  and  in  accordance 
with  the  nature  of  things,  a  man  is  never  angry  with  himself. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  Philosopher  [Rhet.  ii.)  assigns  as  one 


520  QUESTION  XLVI 

difference  between  hatred  and  anger,  that  hatred  may  be 
felt  towards  a  class,  as  we  hate  the  entire  class  of  thieves  ; 
whereas  anger  is  directed  only  towards  an  individiial.  The 
reason  is  that  hatred  arises  from  our  considering  a  quality 
as  disagreeing  with  our  disposition;  and  this  may  refer  to 
a  thing  in  general  or  in  particular.  Anger,  on  the  other 
hand,  ensues  from  someone  having  injured  us  by  his  action. 
Now  all  actions  are  the  deeds  of  individuals  :  and  conse- 
quently anger  is  always  pointed  at  an  individual. — When 
the  whole  state  hurts  us,  the  whole  state  is  reckoned  as  one 
individual. 

Eighth  Article. 

whether  the  species  of  anger  are  suitably 

assigned  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Eighth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  Damascene  [De  Fide  Orthod.  ii.) 
unsuitably  assigns  three  species  of  anger, — wrath,  ill-will 
and  rancotir.  For  no  genus  derives  its  specific  differences 
from  accidents.  But  these  three  are  diversified  in  respect 
of  an  accident:  because  the  beginning  of  the  movement  of 
anger  is  called  wrath  (^^0X09) ,  if  anger  continue  it  is  called  ill- 
will  [firjvis:) ;  while  rancour  (koto^)  is  anger  waiting  for  an 
opportunity  of  vengeance.  Therefore  these  are  not  different 
species  of  anger. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  Tully  says  [Quaest.  Tusc.  iv.)  that  ex- 
candescentia  [irascibility)  is  what  the  Greeks  call  Ov/jlco(ti<;, 
and  is  a  kind  of  anger  that  arises  and  subsides  intermittently  ; 
while  according  to  Damascene  Ov^coat^;  is  the  same  as  a:oto9 
[rancour] .  Therefore  k6to^  does  not  bide  its  time  for  taking 
vengeance,  but  in  course  of  time  spends  itself. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  Gregory  [Moral,  xxi.)  gives  three  degrees 
of  anger,  namely,  anger  without  utterance,  anger  with  utter- 
ance, anger  with  perfection  of  speech,  corresponding  to  the 
three  degrees  mentioned  by  Our  Lord  (Matth.  v.  22) :  Who- 
soever is  angry  with  his  brother  (thus  implying  anger  without 
utterance),  and  then,  whoever  shall  say  to  his  brother,  '  Raca  ' 
(implying  anger  with  utterance),  and  lastly,  whosoever  shall 


OF  ANGER,  IN  ITSELF  521 

say  '  Thou  fool'  (where  we  have  perfection  of  speech). 
Therefore  Damascene's  division  is  imperfect,  since  it  takes 
no  account  of  utterance. 

On  the  contrary  stands  the  authority  of  Damascene  [loc. 
cit.)  and  Gregory  of  Nyssa  (Nemesius,  De  Nat.  Horn.  xxi.). 

I  answer  that,  The  species  of  anger  given  by  Damascene 
and  Gregory  of  Nyssa  are  taken  from  those  things  which 
give  increase  to  anger.  This  happens  in  three  ways.  First 
from  the  facility  of  the  movement  itself,  and  he  calls  this 
kind  of  anger  ;^oXo9  [hile)  because  it  is  quickly  aroused. 
Secondly,  on  the  part  of  the  grief  that  causes  anger,  and 
which  dwells  some  time  in  the  memory ;  this  belongs  to  /ATji^t? 
(ill-zmll)  which  is  derived  from  jjueveiv  {to  dwell) .  Thirdly,  on 
the  part  of  that  which  the  angry  man  seeks,  viz.,  vengeance ; 
and  this  pertains  to  k6to<;  {rancour)  which  never  rests  until 
it  is  avenged.  Hence  the  Philosopher  {Ethic,  iv.)  calls 
some  angry  persons  aKpoxoXoc  {choleric),  because  they  are 
easily  angered;  some  he  calls  TriKpoi  {bitter),  because  they 
retain  their  anger  for  a  long  time ;  and  some  he  calls  ^aXeTroL 
{ill-tempered) ,  because  they  never  rest  until  they  have  re- 
taliated. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  All  those  things  which  give  anger  some  kind 
of  perfection  are  not  altogether  accidental  to  anger;  and 
consequently  nothing  prevents  them  from  causing  a  certain 
specific  difference  thereof. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Irascibility,  which  Tully  mentions,  seems 
to  pertain  to  the  first  species  of  anger,  which  consists  in  a 
certain  quickness  of  temper,  rather  than  to  rancour  {furor) . 
And  there  is  no  reason  why  the  Greek  OvfiMcri^,  which  is 
denoted  by  the  Latin  furor,  should  not  signify  both  quick- 
ness to  anger,  and  firmness  of  purpose  in  being  avenged. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  These  degrees  are  distinguished  according 
to  various  effects  of  anger;  and  not  according  to  degrees  of 
perfection  in  the  very  movement  of  anger. 


QUESTION  XLVII. 

OF  THE  CAUSE  THAT  PROVOKES  ANGER,  AND  OF  ITS 

REMEDIES.* 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  cause  that  provokes  anger,  and 
its  remedies.  Under  this  head  there  are  four  points  of 
inquiry:  (i)  Whether  the  motive  of  anger  is  always  some- 
thing done  against  the  one  who  is  angry  ?  (2)  Whether 
shght  or  contempt  is  the  sole  motive  of  anger  ?  (3)  Of  the 
cause  of  anger  on  the  part  of  the  angry  person.  (4)  Of  the 
cause  of  anger  on  the  part  of  the  person  with  whom  one  is 
angry. 

First  Article. 

whether  the  motive  of  anger  is  always  some- 
thing done  against  the  one  who  is  angry  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  the  motive  of  anger  is  not 
always  something  done  against  the  one  who  is  angry. 
Because  man,  by  sinning,  can  do  nothing  against  God; 
since  it  is  written  (Job  xxxv.  6) :  If  thy  iniquities  be  multi- 
plied, what  shalt  thou  do  against  Him  ?  And  yet  God  is 
spoken  of  as  being  angry  with  man  on  account  of  sin, 
according  to  Ps.  cv.  40 :  The  Lord  was  exceedingly  angry  with 
His  people.  Therefore  it  is  not  always  on  account  of 
something  done  against  him,  that  a  man  is  angry. 

Ob).  2.  Further,  anger  is  a  desire  for  vengeance.  But 
one  may  desire  vengeance  for  things  done  against  others. 

*  There  is  no  further  mention  of  these  remedies  in  the  text. 

522 


THE  CAUSE  OF  ANGER  523 

Therefore  we  are  not  always  angry  on  account  of  something 
done  against  us. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  as  the  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.)  man  is 
angry  especially  with  those  le^ho  despise  what  he  takes  a  great 
interest  in  ;  thus  men  who  study  philosophy  are  angry  with 
those  who  despise  philosophy,  and  so  forth.  But  contempt 
of  philosophy  does  not  harm  the  philosopher.  Therefore 
it  is  not  always  a  harm  done  to  us  that  makes  us  angry. 

Obj.  4.  Further,  he  that  holds  his  tongue  when  another 
insults  him,  provokes  him  to  greater  anger,  as  Chrysostom 
observes  {Horn.  xxii.  in  Ep.  ad  Rom.).  But  by  holding 
his  tongue  he  does  the  other  no  harm.  Therefore  a  man  is 
not  always  provoked  to  anger  by  something  done  against 
him. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.)  that 
anger  is  always  diie  to  something  done  to  oneself :  whereas 
hatred  may  arise  without  anything  being  done  to  us,  for  we 
hate  a  man  simply  because  we  think  him  such. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XLVL,  A.  6),  anger  is 
the  desire  to  hurt  another  for  the  purpose  of  just  vengeance. 
Now  unless  some  injury  has  been  done,  there  is  no  question 
of  vengeance :  nor  does  any  injury  provoke  one  to  vengeance, 
but  only  that  which  is  done  to  the  person  who  seeks  ven- 
geance: for  just  as  everything  naturally  seeks  its  own  good, 
so  does  it  naturally  repel  its  own  evil.  But  injury  done 
by  anyone  does  not  affect  a  man  unless  in  some  way  it  be 
something  done  against  him.  Consequently  the  motive  of 
a  man's  anger  is  always  something  done  against  him. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  We  speak  of  anger  in  God,  not  as  of  a  passion 
of  the  soul  but  as  of  a  judgment  of  justice,  inasmuch  as 
He  wills  to  take  vengeance  on  sin.  Because  the  sinner,  by 
sinning,  cannot  do  God  any  actual  harm:  but  so  far  as  he 
himself  is  concerned,  he  acts  against  God  in  two  ways. 
First,  in  so  far  as  he  despises  God  in  His  commandments. 
Secondly,  in  so  far  as  he  harms  himself  or  another;  which 
injury  redounds  to  God,  inasmuch  as  the  person  injured 
is  an  object  of  God's  providence  and  protection. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  If  we  are  angry  with  those  who  harm  others, 


524  QUESTION  XLVII 

and  seek  to  be  avenged  on  them,  it  is  because  those  who  are 
injured  belong  in  some  way  to  us:  either  by  some  kinship 
or  by  friendship,  or  at  least  because  of  the  nature  we  have 
in  common. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  When  we  take  a  very  great  interest  in  a 
thing,  we  look  upon  it  as  our  own  good;  so  that  if  anyone 
despise  it,  it  seems  as  though  we  ourselves  were  despised 
and  injured. 

Reply  Ohj.  4.  Silence  provokes  the  insulter  to  anger  when 
he  thinks  it  is  due  to  contempt,  as  though  his  anger  were 
slighted:  and  a  slight  is  an  action. 

Second  Article. 

whether  the  sole  motive  of  anger  is  slight  or 

contempt  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  slight  or  contempt  is  not  the 
sole  motive  of  anger.  For  Damascene  says  {De  Fide 
Orthod.  ii.)  that  we  are  angry  when  we  suffer,  or  think  that 
we  are  suffering,  an  injury.  But  one  may  suffer  an  injury 
without  being  despised  or  slighted.  Therefore  a  slight  is 
not  the  only  motive  of  anger. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  desire  for  honour  and  grief  for  a  slight 
belong  to  the  same  subject.  But  dumb  animals  do  not 
desire  honour.  Therefore  they  are  not  grieved  by  being 
slighted.  And  yet  they  are  roused  to  anger,  when  wo^mded, 
as  the  Philosopher  says  (Ethic,  iii.).  Therefore  a  slight  is 
not  the  sole  motive  of  anger. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  Philosopher  [Rhet.  ii.)  gives  many 
other  causes  of  anger,  for  instance,  being  forgotten  by  others  ; 
that  others  should  rejoice  in  our  misfortunes  ;  that  they  should 
make  known  our  evils  ;  being  hindered  from  doing  as  we  like. 
Therefore  being  slighted  is  not  the  only  motive  for  being  angry . 

On  the  contrary.  The  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.)  that  anger 
is  a  desire,  with  sorrow,  for  vengeance,  on  account  of  a  seeming 
slight  done  unbecomingly. 

I  answer  that.   All  the  causes  of  anger  are  reduced  to 


THE  CAUSE  OF  ANGER  525 

slight.  For  slight  is  of  three  kinds,  as  stated  in  Rhet.  ii.^ 
viz.,  contempt,  despiteful  treatment,  i.e.,  hindering  one  from 
doing  one's  will,  and  insolence  :  and  all  motives  of  anger  are 
reduced  to  these  three.  Two  reasons  may  be  assigned  for 
this.  First,  because  anger  seeks  another's  hurt  as  being 
a  means  of  just  vengeance:  wherefore  it  seeks  vengeance  in 
so  far  as  it  seems  just.  Now  just  vengeance  is  taken  only 
for  that  which  is  done  unjustly;  hence  that  which  provokes 
anger  is  always  something  considered  in  the  light  of  an 
injustice.  Wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  [Rhet.  ii.)  that 
men  are  not  angry, — if  they  think  that  they  have  wronged  some 
one  and  are  siiffering  justly  on  that  account ;  because  there  is 
no  anger  at  what  is  just.  Now  injury  is  done  to  another  in 
three  ways:  namely,  through  ignorance,  through  passion, 
and  through  choice.  Then,  most  of  all,  a  man  does  an 
injustice,  when  he  does  it  from  choice,  on  purpose,  or  from 
deliberate  malice,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  v.  Wherefore  we  are 
most  of  all  angry  with  those  who,  in  our  opinion,  have  hurt 
us  on  purpose.  For  if  we  think  that  some  one  has  done  us 
an  injury  through  ignorance  or  through  passion,  either  we 
are  not  angry  with  them  at  all,  or  very  much  less:  since  to 
do  anything  through  ignorance  or  through  passion  takes 
away  from  the  notion  of  injury,  and  to  a  certain  extent  calls 
for  mercy  and  forgiveness.  Those,  on  the  other  hand,  who 
do  an  injury  on  purpose,  seem  to  sin  from  contempt;  where- 
fore we  are  angr}-  with  them  most  of  all.  Hence  the  Philoso- 
pher says  {Rhet.  ii.)  that  we  are  either  not  angry  at  all,  or 
not  very  angry  with  those  who  have  acted  through  anger,  because 
they  do  not  seem  to  have  acted  slightingly. 

The  second  reason  is  because  a  slight  is  opposed  to  a 
man's  excellence:  because  men  think  little  of  things  that  are 
not  worth  much  ado  [Rhet.  ii.).  Now  we  seek  for  some  kind 
of  excellence  from  all  our  goods.  Consequently  whatever 
injury  is  inflicted  on  us,  in  so  far  as  it  is  derogatory  to  our 
excellence,  seems  to  savour  of  a  slight. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Any  other  cause,  besides  contempt,  through 
which  a  man  suffers  an  injury,  takes  away  from  the  notion 
of  injury:   contempt   or  slight  alone  adds  to   the  motive 


526  QUESTION  XLVII 

of  anger,  and  consequently  is  of  itself  the  cause  of 
anger. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  Although  a  dumb  animal  does  not  seek 
honour  as  such,  yet  it  naturally  seeks  a  certain  superiority, 
and  is  angry  with  anything  derogatory  thereto. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Each  of  those  causes  amounts  to  some  kind 
of  slight.  Thus  forgetfulness  is  a  clear  sign  of  slight  esteem, 
for  the  more  we  think  of  a  thing  the  more  is  it  fixed  in  our 
memory.  Again  if  a  man  does  not  hesitate  by  his  remarks- 
to  give  pain  to  another,  this  seems  to  show  that  he  thinks 
little  of  him :  and  those  too  who  show  signs  of  hilarity  when 
another  is  in  misfortune,  seem  to  care  little  about  his  good 
or  evil.  Again  he  that  hinders  another  from  carrying  out 
his  will;  without  deriving  thereby  any  profit  to  himself, 
seems  not  to  care  much  for  his  friendship.  Consequently 
all  those  things,  in  so  far  as  they  are  signs  of  contempt, 
provoke  anger. 

Third  Article. 

WHETHER  A  MAN'S   EXCELLENCE   IS   THE   CAUSE   OF   HIS 

BEING   ANGRY  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  man's  excellence  is  not  the 
cause  of  his  being  more  easily  angry.  For  the  Philosopher 
says  [Rhet.  ii.)  that  some  are  angry  especially  when  they  are 
grieved,  for  instance,  the  sick,  the  poor,  and  those  who  are 
disappointed.  But  these  things  seem  to  pertain  to  defect. 
Therefore  defect  rather  than  excellence  makes  one  prone 
to  anger. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  (ibid.)  that  some 
are  very  much  inclined  to  he  angry  when  they  are  despised 
for  some  failing  or  weakness  of  the  existence  of  which  there  are 
grounds  for  suspicion  ;  hut  if  they  think  they  excel  in  those 
points,  they  do  not  trouble.  But  a  suspicion  of  this  kind  is 
due  to  some  defect.  TherefoT  e  defect  rather  than  excellence 
is  a  cause  of  a  man  being  angry. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  whatever  savours  of  excellence  makes 
a  man  agreeable  and  hopeful.     But  the  Philosopher  says 


THE  CAUSE  OF  ANGER  527 

[Rhet.  ii.)  that  men  are  not  angry  when  they  flay,  make  jokes, 
or  take  part  in  a  feast,  nor  when  they  are  prosperous  or  success- 
ful, nor  in  moderate  pleasures  and  well-founded  hope.  There- 
fore excellence  is  not  a  cause  of  anger. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Philosopher  says  {ibid.)  that  excel- 
lence makes  men  prone  to  anger. 

/  answer  that,  The  cause  of  anger,  in  the  man  who  is  angry, 
ma}^  be  taken  in  two  ways.  First  in  respect  of  the  motive 
of  anger:  and  thus  excellence  is  the  cause  of  a  man  being 
easily  angered.  Because  the  motive  of  anger  is  an  unjust 
slight,  as  stated  above  (A.  2).  Now  it  is  evident  that  the 
more  excellent  a  man  is,  the  more  unjust  is  a  slight  offered 
him  in  the  matter  in  which  he  excels.  Consequently  those 
who  excel  in  any  matter,  are  most  of  all  angry,  if  they  be 
slighted  in  that  matter;  for  instance,  a  wealthy  man  in  his 
riches,  or  an  orator  in  his  eloquence,  and  so  forth. 

Secondly,  the  cause  of  anger,  in  the  man  who  is  angry, 
may  be  considered  on  the  part  of  the  disposition  produced 
in  him  by  the  motive  aforesaid.  Now  it  is  evident  that 
nothing  moves  a  man  to  anger  except  a  hurt  that  grieves 
him:  while  whatever  savours  of  defect  is  above  all  a  cause 
of  grief;  since  men  who  suffer  from  some  defect  are  more 
easily  hurt.  iVnd  this  is  why  men  who  are  weak,  or  subject 
to  some  other  defect,  are  more  easily  angered,  since  they  are 
more  easily  grieved. 

This  suffices  for  the  Reply  to  the  First  Objection. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  If  a  man  be  despised  in  a  matter  in  which 
he  evidently  excels  greatty,  he  does  not  consider  himself 
the  loser  thereby,  and  therefore  is  not  grieved:  and  in  this 
respect  he  is  less  angered.  But  in  another  respect,  in  so  far 
as  he  suffers  a  greater  indignity  through  being  despised,  he 
has  more  reason  for  being  angry:  unless  perhaps  he  thinks 
that  he  is  envied  or  insulted  not  through  contempt  but 
through  ignorance,  or  some  other  like  cause. 

Reply  Ghj.  3.  All  these  things  hinder  anger  in  so  far  as 
they  hinder  sorrow.  But  in  another  respect  they  are 
naturally  apt  to  provoke  anger,  because  they  make  it  more 
unseemly  to  insult  anyone. 


528  QUESTION  XLVII 


Fourth  Article. 

whether  a  person's  defect  is  a  reason  for  being 
more  easily  angry  with  him  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  a  person's  defect  is  not  a  reason 
for  being  more  easily  angry  with  him.  For  the  Philosopher 
says  [Rhet.  ii.)  that  we  are  not  angry  with  those  who  confess 
and  repent  and  hiimhle  themselves  ;  on  the  contrary^  we  are 
gentle  with  them.  Wherefore  dogs  bite  not  those  who  sit  still. 
But  these  things  savour  of  littleness  and  defect.  Therefore 
littleness  of  a  person  is  a  reason  for  being  less  angry  with 
him. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  there  is  no  greater  defect  than  death. 
But  anger  ceases  at  the  sight  of  death.  Therefore  defect 
of  a  person  does  not  provoke  anger  against  him. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  no  one  thinks  little  of  a  man  through  his 
being  friendly  towards  him.  But  we  are  more  angry  with 
friends,  if  they  offend  us  or  refuse  to  help  us;  hence  it  is 
written  (Ps.  liv.  13) :  //  my  enemy  had  reviled  me  I  would 
verily  have  borne  with  it.  Therefore  a  person's  defect  is  not 
a  reason  for  being  more  easily  angry  with  him. 

On  the  contrary,  The  Philosopher  says  {Rhet.  ii.)  that  the 
rich  man  is  angry  with  the  poor  man,  if  the  latter  despise  him  ; 
and  in  like  manner  the  prince  is  angry  with  his  subject. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (AA.  2,  3),  unmerited  con- 
tempt more  than  anything  else  is  a  provocative  of  anger. 
Consequently  deficiency  or  littleness  in  the  person  with 
whom  we  are  angry,  tends  to  increase  our  anger,  in  so  far 
as  it  adds  to  the  indignity  of  being  despised.  For  just  as 
the  higher  a  man's  position  the  greater  the  indignity  in 
despising  him;  so  the  less  exalted  a  man  is,  the  greater  the 
indignity  in  being  despised  by  him.  Thus  a  nobleman  is 
angry  if  he  be  insulted  by  a  peasant;  a  wise  man,  if  by  a 
fool;  a  master,  if  by  a  servant. 

If,  however,  the  littleness  or  deficiency  lessens  the  in- 
dignity of  the  contempt,  then  it  does  not  increase  but 


THE  CAUSE  OF  ANGER  529 

lessens  anger.  In  this  way  those  who  repent  of  their  ill- 
deeds,  and  confess  that  they  have  done  wrong,  who  are 
humbled  and  ask  pardon,  mitigate  anger,  according  to 
Prov.  XV.  I :  A  mild  answer  breaketh  wrath  :  because,  to  wit, 
they  seem  not  to  despise,  but  rather  to  think  much  of  those 
before  whom  they  humble  themselves. 

This  suffices  for  the  Reply  to  the  First  Objection. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  There  are  two  reasons  why  anger  ceases  at 
the  sight  of  death.  One  is  because  the  dead  are  incapable 
of  sorrow  and  sensation ;  and  this  is  chiefly  what  the  angry 
seek  in  those  with  whom  they  are  angered. — Another  reason 
is  because  the  dead  seem  to  have  attained  to  the  limit  of 
evils.  Hence  anger  ceases  in  regard  to  all  who  are  grievously 
hurt,  in  so  far  as  this  hurt  surpasses  the  measure  of  just 
retaliation. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  To  be  despised  by  one's  friends  seems  also 
a  greater  indignity.  Consequently  if  they  despise  us  by 
hurting  or  by  failing  to  help,  we  are  angry  with  them  for 
the  same  reason  for  which  we  are  angry  with  those  who  are 
beneath  us. 


II.  I  34 


QUESTION  XLVIII.    • 

OF  THE  EFFECTS  OF  ANGER. 

{In  Four  Articles.) 

We  must  now  consider  the  effects  of  anger :  under  which  head 
there  are  four  points  of  inquiry:  (i)  Whether  anger  causes 
pleasure  ?  (2)  Whether  above  all  it  causes  heat  in  the 
heart  ?  (3)  Whether  above  all  it  hinders  the  use  of  reason  ? 
(4)  Whether  it  causes  taciturnity  ? 

First  Article, 
whether  anger  causes  pleasure  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  First  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  anger  does  not  cause  pleasure. 
Because  sorrow  excludes  pleasure.  But  anger  is  never 
without  sorrow,  since,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  vii.,  everyone  that 
acts  from  anger,  acts  with  pain.  Therefore  anger  does  not 
cause  pleasure. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  iv.)  that 
vengeance  makes  anger  to  cease,  because  it  substitutes  pleasure 
for  pain  :  whence  we  may  gather  that  the  angry  man  derives 
pleasure  from  vengeance,  and  that  vengeance  quells  his 
anger.  Therefore  on  the  advent  of  pleasure,  anger  departs : 
and  consequently  anger  is  not  an  effect  united  with  pleasure. 

Obj.  3.  Further,  no  effect  hinders  its  cause,  since  it  is 
conformed  to  its  cause.  But  pleasure  hinders  anger,  as 
stated  in  Rhet.  ii.     Therefore  pleasure  is  not  an  effect  of  anger. 

On  the  contrary.  The  Philosopher  {ibid.)  quotes  the  saying 
that  anger  is 

"  Sweet  to  the  soul  as  honey  to  the  taste." 

—Iliad,  xviii.  109,  no;  trl.  Pope. 

530 


THE  EFFECTS  OF  ANGER  531 

/  answer  that,  As  the  Philosopher  says  {Ethic,  vii.), 
pleasures,  chiefly  sensible  and  bodily  pleasures,  are  remedies 
against  sorrow:  and  therefore  the  greater  the  sorrow  or 
anxiety,  the  more  sensible  are  we  to  the  pleasure  which  heals 
it,  as  is  evident  in  the  case  of  thirst  which  increases  the 
pleasure  of  drink.  Now  it  is  clear  from  what  has  been  said 
(Q.  XLVIL,  AA.  I,  3),  that  the  movement  of  anger  arises 
from  a  wrong  done  that  causes  sorrow,  for  which  sorrow 
vengeance  is  sought  as  a  remedy.  Consequently  as  soon  as 
vengeance  is  present,  pleasure  ensues,  and  so  much  the 
greater  according  as  the  sorrow  was  greater. — ^Therefore  if 
vengeance  be  really  present,  perfect  pleasure  ensues,  entirely 
excluding  sorrow,  so  that  the  movement  of  anger  ceases. — 
But  before  vengeance  is  really  present,  it  becomes  present 
to  the  angry  man  in  two  ways: — in  one  way,  by  hope;  be- 
cause none  is  angry  except  he  hopes  for  vengeance,  as  stated 
above  (Q.  XLVL,  A.  i) ; — in  another  way,  by  thinking  of  it 
continually,  for  to  everyone  that  desires  a  thing  it  is 
pleasant  to  dwell  on  the  thought  of  what  he  desires ;  where- 
fore the  imaginings  of  dreams  are  pleasant.  Accordingly  an 
angry  man  takes  pleasure  in  thinking  about  vengeance. 
This  pleasure,  however,  is  not  perfect,  so  as  to  banish  sorrow 
and  consequently  anger. 

Reply  Ohj.  i.  The  angry  man  does  not  grieve  and  rejoice 
at  the  same  thing;  he  grieves  for  the  wrong  done,  while  he 
takes  pleasure  in  the  thought  and  hope  of  vengeance.  Con- 
sequently sorrow  is  to  anger  as  its  beginning ;  while  pleasure 
is  the  effect  or  terminus  of  anger. 

Reply  Ohj.  2.  This  argument  holds  in  regard  to  pleasure 
caused  by  the  real  presence  of  vengeance,  which  banishes 
anger  altogether. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Pleasure  that  precedes  hinders  sorrow  from 
ensuing,  and  consequently  is  a  hindrance  to  anger.  But 
pleasure  felt  in  taking  vengeance  follows  from  vengeance. 


532  QUESTION  XLVIII 

Second  Article, 
whether  anger  above  all  causes  fervour  in  the  heart  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Second  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  heat  is  not  above  all  the  effect 
of  anger.  For  fervour,  as  stated  above  (Q.  XXVIII.,  A.  5; 
Q.  XXXVII.,  A.  2),  belongs  to  love.  But  love,  as  above 
stated,  is  the  beginning  and  cause  of  all  the  passions.  Since 
then  the  cause  is  more  powerful  than  its  effect,  it  seems  that 
anger  is  not  the  chief  cause  of  fervour. 

Ohj.  2.  Further,  those  things  which,  of  themselves,  arouse 
fervour,  increase  as  time  goes  on;  thus  love  grows  stronger 
the  longer  it  lasts.  But  in  course  of  time  anger  grows 
weaker;  for  the  Philosopher  says  (Rhet.  ii.)  that  time  puts 
an  end  to  anger.  Therefore  fervour  is  not  the  proper  effect 
of  anger. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  fervour  added  to  fervour  produces  greater 
fervour.  But  the  addition  of  a  greater  anger  banishes  already 
existing  anger,  as  the  Philosopher  says  [ibid.).  Therefore 
anger  does  not  cause  fervour. 

On  the  contrary,  Damascene  says  that  anger  is  fervour  of 
the  blood  around  the  heart,  resulting  from  an  exhalation  of  the 
bile. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (Q.  XLIV.,  A.  i),  the  bodily 
transmutation  that  occurs  in  the  passions  of  the  soul,  is  pro- 
portionate to  the  movement  of  the  appetite.  Now  it  is 
evident  that  every  appetite,  even  the  natural  appetite, 
tends  with  greater  force  to  repel  that  which  is  contrary  to  it, 
if  it  be  present:  hence  we  see  that  hot  water  freezes  harder, 
as  though  the  cold  acted  with  greater  force  on  the  hot  object. 
Since  then  the  appetitive  movement  of  anger  is  caused  by 
some  injury  inflicted,  as  by  a  contrary  that  is  present;  it 
follows  that  the  appetite  tends  with  great  force  to  repel  the 
injury  by  the  desire  of  vengeance;  and  hence  ensues  great 
vehemence  and  impetuosity  in  the  movement  of  anger. 
And  because  the  movement  of  anger  is  not  one  of  recoil, 
which  corresponds  to  the  action  of  cold,  but  one  of  prosecu- 


THE  EFFECTS  OF  ANGER  533 

tion,  which  corresponds  to  the  action  of  heat,  the  result  is 
that  the  movement  of  anger  produces  fervour  of  the  blood 
and  vital  spirits  around  the  heart,  which  is  the  instrument 
of  the  soul's  passions.  And  hence  it  is  that,  on  account  of 
the  heart  being  so  disturbed  by  anger,  those  chiefly  who  are 
angry  betray  signs  thereof  in  their  outer  members.  For, 
as  Gregory  says  [Moral,  v.)  the  heart  that  is  inflamed  with  the 
stings  of  its  oivn  anger  heats  quick,  the  body  trembles,  the  tongue 
stammers,  the  countenance  takes  fire,  the  eyes  grow  fierce,  they 
that  are  well  known  are  not  recognized.  With  the  mouth  indeed 
he  shapes  a  sound,  but  the  understanding  knows  not  what  it 
says. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Love  itself  is  not  felt  so  keenly  as  in  the  absence 
of  the  beloved,  as  Augustine  observes  [De  Trin.  x.).  Conse- 
quently when  a  man  suffers  from  a  hurt  done  to  the  excel- 
lence that  he  loves,  he  feels  his  love  thereof  the  more :  the 
result  being  that  his  heart  is  moved  with  greater  heat  to 
remove  the  hindrance  to  the  object  of  his  love:  so  that 
anger  increases  the  fervour  of  love  and  makes  it  to  be  felt 
more. 

Nevertheless,  the  fervour  arising  from  heat  differs  accord- 
ing as  it  is  to  be  referred  to  love  or  to  anger.  Because  the 
fervour  of  love  has  a  certain  sweetness  and  gentleness;  for 
it  tends  to  the  good  that  one  loves:  whence  it  is  likened  to 
the  warmth  of  the  air  and  of  the  blood.  For  this  reason 
sanguine  temperaments  are  more  inclined  to  love;  and 
hence  the  saying  that  love  springs  from  the  liver,  because  of 
the  blood  being  formed  there.— On  the  other  hand,  the 
fervour  of  anger  has  a  certain  bitterness  with  a  tendency 
to  destroy,  for  it  seeks  to  be  avenged  on  the  contrary 
evil:  whence  it  is  likened  to  the  heat  of  fire  and  of 
the  bile,  and  for  this  reason  Damascene  says  [loc.  cit.) 
that  it  results  from  an  exhalation  of  the  bile  iii)hence  it  takes 
its  name  %o\^. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  Time,  of  necessity,  weakens  all  those  things, 
the  causes  of  which  are  impaired  by  time.  Now  it  is  evident 
that  memory  is  weakened  by  time ;  for  things  which  happened 
long  ago  easily  slip  from  our  memory.     But  anger  is  caused 


534  QUESTION  XLVIII 

by  the  memory  of  a  wrong  done.  Consequently  the  cause 
of  anger  is  impaired  little  by  little  as  time  goes  on,  until  at 
length  it  vanishes  altogether. — Moreover  a  wrong  seems 
greater  when  it  is  first  felt;  and  our  estimate  thereof  is 
gradually  lessened  the  further  the  sense  of  present  wTong 
recedes  into  the  past. — The  same  applies  to  love,  so  long  as 
the  cause  of  love  is  in  the  memory  alone:  wherefore  the 
Philosopher  says  [Ethic,  vii.)  that  if  a  friend's  absence  lasts 
long,  it  seems  to  produce  a  cessation  of  friendship.  But  in 
the  presence  of  a  friend,  the  cause  of  friendship  is  continually 
being  multiplied  by  time :  wherefore  the  friendship  increases : 
and  the  same  would  apply  to  anger,  were  its  cause  continually 
multiplied. 

Nevertheless  the  very  fact  that  anger  soon  spends  itself 
proves  the  strength  of  its  fervour :  for  as  a  great  fire  is  soon 
spent  having  burnt  up  all  the  fuel ;  so  too  anger,  by  reason 
of  its  vehemence,  soon  dies  away. 

Reply  Ohj.  3.  Every  power  that  is  divided  in  itself  is 
weakened.  Consequently  if  a  man  being  already  angry 
with  one,  becomes  angry  with  another,  by  this  very  fact  his 
anger  with  the  former  is  weakened.  Especially  is  this  so 
if  his  anger  in  the  second  case  be  greater :  because  the  wrong 
done  which  aroused  his  former  anger,  will,  in  comparison 
with  the  second  wrong,  which  is  reckoned  greater,  seem  to 
be  of  little  or  no  account. 


Third  Article, 
whether  anger  above  all  hinders  the  use  of  reason  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Third  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  anger  does  not  hinder  the  use 
of  reason.  Because  that  which  presupposes  an  act  of  reason, 
does  not  seem  to  hinder  the  use  of  reason.  But  anger  follows 
reason,  as  stated  in  Ethic,  vii.  [Problem,  xxviii. ;  cf.  Ethic,  vii.). 
Therefore  anger  does  not  hinder  reason. 

Obj.  2.  Further,  the  more  the  reason  is  hindered,  the  less 
does  man  show  his  thoughts.  But  the  Philosopher  says 
[Ethic,  vii.)  that  an  angry  man  is  not  cunning  hut  shows 


THE  EFFECTS  OF  ANGER  535 

what  he  thinks.  Therefore  anger  does  not  seem  to  hinder 
the  use  of  reason,  as  desire  does;  for  desire  is  cunning,  as  he 
also  states  [ibid.). 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  the  judgment  of  reason  becomes  more 
evident  by  juxtaposition  of  the  contrary :  because  contraries 
stand  out  more  clearly  when  placed  beside  one  another. 
But  this  also  increases  anger:  for  the  Philosopher  says 
{Rhet.  ii.)  that  men  are  more  angry  if  they  receive  unwonted 
treatment  ;  for  instance  ^  honourable  men,  if  they  be  dishonoured  : 
and  so  forth.  Therefore  the  same  cause  increases  anger, 
and  facilitates  the  judgment  of  reason.  Therefore  anger 
does  not  hinder  the  judgment  of  reason. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  'says  [Moral,  v.)  that  anger 
withdraws  the  light  of  understanding,  while  by  agitating  it 
troubles  the  mind. 

I  answer  that,  Although  the  mind  or  reason  makes  no  use 
of  a  bodily  organ  in  its  proper  act,  yet,  since  it  needs  certain 
sensitive  powers  for  the  execution  of  its  act,  the  acts  of 
which  powers  are  hindered  when  the  body  is  disturbed,  it 
follows  of  necessity  that  any  disturbance  in  the  body  hinders 
even  the  judgment  of  reason;  as  is  clear  in  the  case  of 
drunkenness  or  sleep.  Now  it  has  been  stated  (A.  2)  that 
anger,  above  all,  causes  a  bodily  disturbance  in  the  region  of 
the  heart,  so  much  as  to  affect  even  the  outward  members. 
Consequently,  of  all  the  passions,  anger  is  the  most  manifest 
obstacle  to  the  judgment  of  reason,  according  to  Ps.  xxx.  10 : 
My  eye  is  troubled  with  wrath. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  The  beginning  of  anger  is  in  the  reason,  as 
regards  the  appetitive  movement,  which  is  the  formal 
element  of  anger.  But  the  passion  of  anger  forestalls  the 
perfect  judgment  of  reason,  as  though  it  listened  but  im- 
perfectly to  reason,  on  account  of  the  commotion  of  the 
heat  urging  to  instant  action,  which  commotion  is  the 
material  element  of  anger.  In  this  respect  it  hinders  the 
judgment  of  reason. 

Reply  Obj.  2.  An  angry  man  is  said  to  show  his  thoughts,  not 
because  it  is  clear  to  him  what  he  ought  to  do,  but  because 
he  acts  openly,  without  thought  of  hiding  himself.     This  is 


536  QUESTION  XLVIII 

due  partly  to  the  reason  being  hindered,  so  as  not  to  discern 
what  should  be  hidden  and  what  done  openly,  nor  to  devise 
the  means  of  hiding ;  and  partly  to  the  dilatation  of  the  heart 
which  pertains  to  magnanimity  which  is  an  effect  of  anger: 
wherefore  the  Philosopher  says  of  the  magnanimous  man 
{Ethic,  iv.)  that  he  is  open  in  his  hatreds  and  his  friendships 
.  .  .  and  speaks  and  acts  openly. — Desire,  on  the  other  hand, 
is  said  to  lie  low  and  to  be  cunning,  because,  in  many  cases, 
the  pleasurable  things  that  are  desired,  savour  of  shame  and 
voluptuousness,  wherein  man  wishes  not  to  be  seen.  But 
in  those  things  that  savour  of  manliness  and  excellence, 
such  as  matters  of  vengeance,  man  seeks  to  be  in  the 
open. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  As  stated  above  {ad  i),  the  movement  of 
anger  begins  in  the  reason,  wherefore  the  juxtaposition  of 
one  contrary  with  another  facilitates  the  judgment  of  reason, 
on  the  same  grounds  as  it  increases  anger.  For  when  a 
man  who  is  possessed  of  honour  or  wealth,  suffers  a  loss 
therein,  this  loss  seems  all  the  greater,  both  on  account  of 
the  contrast,  and  because  it  was  unforeseen.  Consequently 
it  causes  greater  grief:  just  as  a  great  good,  through  being 
received  unexpectedly,  causes  greater  delight.  And  in 
proportion  to  the  increase  of  the  grief  that  precedes, 
anger  is  increased  also. 


Fourth  Article, 
whether  anger  above  all  causes  taciturnity  ? 

We  proceed  thus  to  the  Fourth  Article  : — 

Objection  i.  It  seems  that  anger  does  not  cause  taciturnity. 
Because  taciturnity  is  opposed  to  speech.  But  increase  of 
anger  conduces  to  speech;  as  is  evident  from  the  degrees 
of  anger  laid  down  by  Our  Lord  (Matth.  v.  22) :  where 
He  says :  Whosoever  is  angry  with  his  brother ;  and  ... 
whosoever  shall  say  to  his  brother,  '  Raca '  ;  and  .  .  .  whoso- 
ever shall  say,  '  Thou  fool.'  Therefore  anger  does  not  cause 
taciturnity. 

Obj.   2.  Further,   through  failing  to   obey  reason,   man 


THE  EFFECTS  OF  ANGER  537 

sometimes  breaks  out  into  unbecoming  words:  hence  it  is 
written  (Prov.  xxv.  28) :  As  a  city  that  lieth  open  and  is  not 
compassed  with  walls,  so  is  a  man  that  cannot  refrain  his  own 
spirit  in  speaking.  But  anger,  above  all,  hinders  the  judg- 
ment of  reason,  as  stated  above  (A.  3).  Consequently  above 
all  it  makes  one  break  out  into  unbecoming  words.  There- 
fore it  does  not  cause  taciturnity. 

Ohj.  3.  Further,  it  is  written  (Matth.  xii.  34):  Out  of  the 
abtmdance  of  the  heart  the  mouth  speaketh.  But  anger,  above 
all,  causes  a  disturbance  in  the  heart,  as  stated  above  (A.  2). 
Therefore  above  all  it  conduces  to  speech.  Therefore  it 
does  not  cause  taciturnity. 

On  the  contrary,  Gregory  says  (Moral,  v.)  that  when  anger 
does  not  vent  itself  outwardly  by  the  lips,  inwardly  it  burns  the 
more  fiercely. 

I  answer  that,  As  stated  above  (A.  3;  Q.  XLVI.,  A.  4), 
anger  both  follows  an  act  of  reason,  and  hinders  the  reason : 
and  in  both  respects  it  may  cause  taciturnity.  On  the  part 
of  the  reason,  when  the  judgment  of  reason  prevails  so  far, 
that  although  it  does  not  curb  the  appetite  in  its  inordinate 
desire  for  vengeance,  yet  it  curbs  the  tongue  from  unbridled 
speech.  Wherefore  Gregory  says  [Moral,  v.) :  Sometimes 
when  the  mind  is  disturbed,  anger,  as  if  in  judgment,  com- 
mands silence. — On  the  part  of  the  impediment  to  reason 
because,  as  stated  above  (A.  2),  the  disturbance  of  anger 
reaches  to  the  outward  members,  and  chiefly  to  those  mem- 
bers which  reflect  more  distinctly  the  emotions  of  the  heart, 
such  as  the  e^^es,  face  and  tonp^ue;  wherefore,  as  observed 
above  (A.  2),  the  tongue  stammers,  the  countenance  takes  fire, 
the  eyes  grow  fierce.  Consequently  anger  may  cause  such  a 
disturbance,  that  the  tongue  is  altogether  deprived  of  speech; 
and  taciturnity  is  the  result. 

Reply  Obj.  i.  Anger  sometimes  goes  so  far  as  to  hinder  the 
reason  from  curbing  the  tongue:  but  sometimes  it  goes  yet 
farther,  so  as  to  paralyze  the  tongue  and  other  outward 
members. 

And  this  suflices  for  the  Reply  to  the  Second  Objection. 

Reply  Obj.  3.  The  disturbance  of  the  heart  may  some- 


538  QUESTION  XLVIII 

times  superabound  to  the  extent  that  the  movements  of  the 
outward  members  are  hindered  by  the  inordinate  movement 
of  the  heart.  Thence  ensue  taciturnity  and  immobiHty  of 
the  outward  members;  and  sometimes  even  death. — If, 
however,  the  disturbance  be  not  so  great,  then  out  of  the 
abundance  of  the  heart  thus  disturbed,  the  mouth  proceeds 
to  speak. 


Printed  in  Enziand 


Return  on 
or  before 


^'. 


■  V'l 


,    /I     'a      -! 


\m  I  ■  '"^^ 


I   IIIIIIIIIIMlillJl^li^Iin?'-''^'  ^"^^^^y 


3  5002  03119  7986 


BX  1749  .T5  1912  2j1:1 

Thomas^  1225? -1274 

The  '^Summa  theological  of 
St.  Thomas  Aquinas