Skip to main content

Full text of "System of Christian ethics"

See other formats


NYPL 


RESEARCH  UBRARIES 


fflSa'3  07997907^ 


SYSTEM 


CHEISTIAN    ETHICS. 


SYSTEM 


or 


CHRISTIAI^    ETHICS. 


BY  '\J 


De.    I?'  A/fooRNER, 


OBERCONSISTORIALKATH   AND   PROFESSOR   OF  THEOLOGY,    BERLIN. 


EDITED   BY 


De.   a.  dorner. 


TRANSLATED   BY 

Professor  CyM;>ilEAD,  D.D., 

FORMERLY   PROFESSOR  OF  HEBREW   IM   ANDOVER  THEOLOGICAL   SEJI1KAR7, 
AND 

Eev.  K.  T.  CUNNINGHAM,  M.A. 


NEW    YORK: 

S  C  E  I  B  N  E  E    &    W  E  L  F  0  E  D. 

1887. 


\ 


\Sec  other  side. 


^^Z- 


M:il--^1yei^- 


Copyright,  1S&7,  hy 

SCEIBNER    &    WeLFORII. 


TRANSLATOR'S  PREFACE. 


Isaac  August  Dorner,  whose  posthumous  worl^  is  here  pre- 
sented to  the  English-reading  public,  w^as  born  June  20, 
1809,  at  Neuhauseu,  in  Southern  Wilrteniberg,  and  died  at 
Wiesbaden,  July  8,  1884.  His  father  was  a  pastor,  and  he 
was  the  sixth  of  twelve  children.  He  enjoyed  from  the  first 
excellent  advantages,  and  was  trained  in  an  atmosphere  of 
piety.  After  studying  at  home  under  a  tutor,  at  a  Latin 
school  in  Tuttlingen,  and  at  another  in  Maulbronn,  he  went 
in  1827  to  Tubingen,  where  he  spent  five  years  at  the 
University  in  the  study  of  philosophy  and  theology.  Having 
passed  the  requisite  examinations,  he  returned  to  his  home 
and  remained  there  two  years,  assisting  his  father  in  his 
ministerial  work.  In  1834  he  was  called  to  Tubingen  as 
rcpetmt  (tutor,  or  fellow)  in  the  theological  department  of 
the  University.  In  1838  he  was  made  extraordinary  pro- 
fessor; and  in  1839  he  was  appointed  ordinary  professor  of 
theology  at  the  University  of  Kiel;  in  1843,  at  Ktinigsberg  : 
in  1847,  at  Bonn  ;  in  1853,  at  Gottingen  ;  in  1862,  at  Berlin, 
where  he  remained  till  the  end  of  his  life. 

Dorner's  outward  life  was  in  general  quiet  and  uneventfuL 
It  was  mostly  filled  with  the  labours  of  the  study  and  the 
lecture-room.  But  his  interest  in  the  world  in  general  was 
lively ;  his  sympathies  were  broad  ;  and  twice  he  travelled 
beyond  the  limits  of  the  continent :  first,  during  his  academic 
career  at  Tubingen,  when  he  visited  Holland,  England,  and 
Scotland  ;  and  next,  in  1873,  when  he  attended  the  meeting 
of  the  Evangelical  Alliance  at  New  York,  where  he  read  a 
paper  on  the  Infallibilism  of  the  Vatican  Council.  He 
was  then  64  years  old;  but  accompanied  by  his  son,  Pro- 
fessor August  Dorner,  the  editor  of  this  treatise,  he  was  able 

h 


vi  translator's  preface. 

to  bear  the  trying  journey,  and  ever  afterwards  rejoiced  in 
the  privilege  of  seeing  again  the  old  acquaintances  and  pupils 
who  there  welcomed  him,  and  in  the  new  scenes  and  friend? 
that  he  there  found.  Not  many  years  after  his  return  he 
began  to  suffer  from  the  incurable  malady  which  ultimately 
terminated  his  life.  Gradually  and  reluctantly  he  relin- 
quished the  discharge  of  his  official  duties,  meeting  students 
finally  in  his  house,  when  he  was  no  longer  able  to  go  to  the 
University.  It  was  during  the  progress  of  this  disease  that 
he  issued  (in  1879-81)  his  Glaulenslchre,  and  (in  1883)  a 
collection  of  his  miscellaneous  articles.  And  finally,  he 
laboured  till  the  very  end  of  his  life  in  preparing  for  the 
press  the  Christliche  Sittenlehre,  a  translation  of  which  is 
herewith  published.  His  mental  faculties  remained  un- 
clouded up  to  the  last  ;  and  in  spite  of  severe  physical 
prostration  he  continued  to  manifest  the  liveliest  interest 
in  the  personal  welfare  of  friends  and  in  the  religious  and 
theological  movements  of  the  day. 

The  last  twenty  years  of  Dorner's  life  were  clouded  by  the 
dementia  of  his  youngest  son — a  youth  of  the  brightest 
promise,  who,  while  pursuing  his  gymnasium  studies,  was 
overtaken  with  the  disease  from  which  he  has  never  recovered. 
To  those  who  knew  the  intensely  domestic  and  affectionate 
nature  of  the  man,  the  manner  in  which  he  bore  this  trial 
was  a  touching  revelation  of  the  depth  of  his  Christian  faith 
and  resignation.  And  when  to  this  affliction  was  added  his 
own  physical  suffering,  his  Christian  character  still  bore  the 
test.  As  Professor  Kleinert  says,  in  his  memorial  address 
before  the  Berlin  Faculty,  "  In  all  this  no  complaint  passed 
over  his  lips,  no  painful  word  concerning  his  bodily  pain. 
Scarcely  a  quiver  of  the  hand,  or  a  tear  in  the  eye,  betrayed 
his  mental  suffering,  when  he  had  to  surrender  to  other  hands 
one  after  another  of  the  official  duties  and  voluntary  labours 
of  benevolence  which  had  grown  into  his  very  heart.  .  .  .  He 
suffered  not  like  a  Stoic,  with  a  heart  steeled  against  the 
Medusa  gaze  of  a  brazen  fate.  He  suffered  like  a  child  of 
God  that  receives  from  the  Father's  hand,  with  unwavering 
trust,  even  what  is  hard  to  bear  ;  like  one  that  has  peace  in 
the  atonement  and  has  hope  reaching  beyond  death." 

This  calm  fortitude  displayed  in  the  crucial  hour  was  but 


TRANSLATOR  S  PREFACE.  VU 

the  natural  expression  of  a  character  formed  long  before. 
Even  one  who  knows  Dorner  merely  as  the  theological  writer 
will  in  his  writings  easily  detect  the  fine  Christian  tone 
which  characterized  the  man ;  but  no  one  who  did  not 
personally  know  him  can  get  a  true  impression  of  the 
Johannean  tenderness  and  childlike  simplicity  which,  dis- 
tinguished him  above  almost  any  one  of  equal  eminence 
and  intellectual  power  whom  the  world  has  ever  known. 
The  most  shrinking  youth,  the  most  timid  foreign  student, 
embarrassed  by  the  consciousness  of  imperfect  acquaintance 
with  the  German  language  and  by  the  fear  of  encroaching 
on  the  time  of  one  who  was  full  of  thought  and  labour,  was 
at  once  put  at  ease  when  he  felt  that  warm  shake  of  the 
hand,  saw  that  indescribably  sweet  smile,  and  heard  those 
cordial,  unaffectedly  kind  tones.  Love  beamed  from  his  eyes 
and  all  his  features.  Professor  Heinrici  of  Marburg  relates,  in 
the  Deutsch-evangelische  Blatter,  his  experience  in  first  forming 
Uorner's  acquaintance.  Armed  with  a  letter  of  introduction, 
he  had  found  his  way  to  the  professor's  room.  "  There  I 
stood  for  the  first  time  before  the  man  from  whom  I  expected 
so  much.  How  differently  I  had  conceived  him  !  I  saw 
no  towering  form,  no  boldly  arched  forehead.  Simply  and 
kindly,  with  a  '  Griiss  Gott,'  he  offered  me  his  hand,  and 
while  he  read  the  letter,  a  gentle  smile  gleamed  on  his  counte- 
nance. As  he  then,  tipping  his  head  slightly  to  the  left  in 
his  peculiar  way,  looked  at  me  with  his  clear  eyes  intently 
and  full  of  kindness,  and  by  his  responsive  questions  drew 
me  40ut  from  my  embarrassment  and  encouraged  me  to  talk, 
I  soon  forgot,  in  inconsiderate  familiarity,  the  value  of  his 
time,  and  was  not  weary  of  telling  him  about  my  vague 
ambitions  and  my  zeal  for  knowledge."  Further  on  the  same 
writer  says,  "  Never  have  I  heard  from  him  a  bitter  word 
about  persons,  even  when  he  gave  expression  to  his  '  ecclesi- 
astical pain  '  and  his  apprehensions  concerning  certain  ten- 
dencies of  theological  inquiry."  This  testimony  could  probably 
be  confirmed  by  all  who  knew  him.  His  was  a  saintliness 
in  which  there  was  no  trace  of  cant  or  of  coldness.  There 
was  that  in  his  whole  demeanour  which  commanded  at  once 
confidence  and  affection.  He  realized  in  a  rare  degree  the 
evangelical    conception   of    the   Christian,    as    one    who    has 


viii  TEANSLATOR  S  PREFACE. 

become  as  a  little  child.  He  retained  to  the  last  his  fond- 
ness for  his  native  place,  and  for  the  relatives  and  friends 
who  still  lived  there.  In  the  commemorative  address  which 
was  delivered  at  the  funeral  services  at  Tuttlingen  by  assistant 
preacher  Knapp,  a  charming  picture  is  given  of  the  visits 
which  Dorner  used  often  to  make  at  Tuttlingen  and  Neu- 
hausen.  "  What  a  festive  occasion  it  was  for  all  his  relatives, 
when  the  revered  '  Uncle  Professor  '  was  again  here,  recognised, 
in  spite  of  his  distance,  as  the  noble  head  of  the  great  family, 
stooping  down  to  the  smallest  child  among  his  relatives  here 
with  a  kind  word  and  a  warm  kiss  !  What  festive  occasions, 
when  in  the  house  or  in  the  garden  the  relatives  were  gathered 
around  him,  and  took  in  the  manna  which  gently  dropped 
from  his  conversation  and  instruction !  For  everything  he 
had  a  sympathetic  feeling ;  every  little  word  that  he  heard  he 
deemed  worthy  of  a  considerate  attention  and  of  a  fitting  and 
helpful  reply." 

It  is  not  strange,  therefore,  that  when  his  death  called 
forth  from  his  numerous  friends  and  admirers  their  judgment 
of  the  man,  stress  was  always  laid  on  his  personal  character  as 
being  the  most  shining  feature  in  him,  though  in  the  galaxy 
of  the  intellectual  and  the  learned  he  also  shone  as  a  star  of 
the  first  magnitude.  Says  Professor  Kleinert  at  the  close  of 
his  address,  "  P>eside  the  torso  of  his  last  w^ork  stands  the 
image  of  his  life,  labour,  and  suffering,  a  model  for  coming 
generations  of  theologians  to  gaze  at — an  ethics,  written  and 
finished  by  the  Spirit  of  Jesus  Christ  who  redeemed  him." 
And  another  of  Dorner's  colleagues,  Professor  Weiss,  echoes 
this  sentiment,  and  adds,  "  Who  could  ever  forget  it,  who 
had  once  come  into  contact  with  him — the  power  of  this 
Christian  personality  which,  just  because  in  its  unadulterated 
simplicity  it  made  no  pretence  to  be  anything,  impressed  one 
all  the  more  powerfully  ?  There  rested  something  of  child- 
like cheerfulness  on  those  dear  features ;  there  beamed  such 
warmth  of  heart  out  of  the  kindly  eyes  ;  his  uniformly  amiable 
spirit  had  for  every  one  a  sympathetic  word  full  of  kindness 
and  gentleness.  And  yet  there  rested  on  his  whole  being  a 
consecration  such  as  is  lent  only  by  the  nobility  of  a  thorough 
sanctification  of  the  inmost  nature  and  by  the  dignity  of  a 
matured   wisdom."     Dorner   did    not   possess   the   aggressive 


TRANSLATORS  PREFACE.  IX 

nature  which  made  Tholuck  so  great  a  power  in  influencing 
the  young.  He  had  not  the  same  Socratic  power  of  drawing 
them  out.  He  had  not  the  many-sidedness  of  mind,  nor  the 
humour,  now  playful  now  grim,  nor  the  facility  of  language, 
which  made  Tholuck  so  successful  in  getting  hold  of  both 
natives  and  foreigners.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  there  was  in 
Dorner  a  depth  and  an  evenness  of  religious  consecration,  a 
poise  and  symmetry  of  character,  which  showed  itself  without 
many  words,  and  which  made  him  as  a  man  even  more  power- 
fully influential  than  his  more  widely  known  contemporary. 
He  uttered  fewer  of  those  epigrammatic  and  striking  sayings 
which  Tholuck's  friends  can  recall  and  quote  as  uttered  by 
him.  But  the  impression  made  by  his  personality,  even 
when  no  utterance  of  his  can  be  distinctly  remembered,  was 
ineffaceable.  Though  he  had  not  so  wide  a  circle  of  acquaint- 
ances as  Tholuck,  he  had  sympathies  no  less  wide.  He  had 
perhaps  even  a  greater  capacity  to  appreciate  what  was  good 
in  other  nations  than  his  own.  He  loved  to  recognise  and 
admire  moral  worth  and  moral  grandeur  wherever  they  were 
to  be  found.  He  reverenced  the  dignity  of  personality.  His 
theology  is  tinctured  with  this  sentiment.  His  own  life  and 
bearing  witnessed  to  the  reality  and  power  of  it.  It  made 
him,  on  the  one  hand,  almost  unique  in  humility ;  it  made 
him,  on  the  other  hand,  untiring  in  his  efforts,  both  philo- 
sophical and  practical,  to  exalt  the  individual  character. 

Although  so  quiet  and  unobtrusive  in  his  manner,  Dorner 
was  a  most  active  man,  making  his  influence  felt  not  only  in 
his  house  and  in  his  lecture-room,  but  in  ecclesiastical  bodies 
of  every  sort,  and  in  the  missionary  activities  of  the  Church. 
He  was  one  of  the  leaders  in  the  founding  of  the  Church 
Diet — a  movement  called  forth  by  the  revolutionary  excite- 
ments of  1848.  He  was  also  prominent  in  advocating  the 
organization  of  an  ecclesiastical  synod,  with  a  view  to  the 
development  of  the  religious  energies  and  independence  of  the 
German  Protestant  Church.  He  was  an  influential  member 
of  the  Oherkirchcnrath,  the  highest  ecclesiastical  body  in 
Prussia.  He  took  an  active  part  in  the  work  of  revising 
Luther's  translation  of  the  Bible.  He  was  an  enthusiastic 
promoter  of  the  cause  of  Inner  Missions.  He  was  connected 
with,  and  deeply  interested  in,  the  work  of  the   Evangelical 


X  TRANSLATOll  S  PREFACE. 

Alliance.  "When  he  was  in  the  United  States,  he  carefully 
observed  the  beneficiary  institutions  designed  for  indigent 
students,  and  perfected  afterwards  the  execution  of  a  similar 
plan  which  he  had  at  heart  for  students  in  Berlin;  the 
so-called  Johanneum  and  the  Melanchthon  House  are  the 
permanent  fruits.  If,  as  compared  with  nearly  all  his  con- 
temporaries, he  stood  in  intellect  and  culture  as  much  above 
them  as  Paul  above  the  other  apostles,  he  could  also,  like 
Paul,  be  said,  in  comparison  with  his  fellows,  to  be  "in 
labours  more  abundant."  Accordingly,  though  Domer  can 
now  safely  be  reckoned  among  the  wise  "  that  shine  as  the 
brightness  of  the  firmament,"  it  is  not  because  he  avoided 
those  conflicts  which  exposed  him  to  opposition  and  even  to 
obloquy.  He  was  gentle,  but  Jio  had  strong  convictions. 
And  his  prominent  position  in  the  practical  direction  of 
ecclesiastical  affairs  brought  him  into  collision  with  many 
even  of  those  who,  in  their  theological  position,  were  at  one 
with  him.  He  was,  and  still  is,  by  many  regarded  as  having 
failed  to  understand  the  best  interests  of  the  Church.  But  his 
motives  were  respected,  even  when  his  measures  were  opposed. 
If  he  sometimes  seemed  to  be  too  indulgent  towards  error,  it 
was  because  he  had  a  deliberate  and  sincere  zeal  for  a  large- 
minded  toleration.  He  deprecated  resort  to  coercive  measures, 
whether  political  or  ecclesiastical.  He  had  an  almost  un- 
bounded confidence  in  tlie  power  of  Christian  truth  and  Chris- 
tian character  to  rectify  and  purify  the  Christian  Church. 
He  believed  in  the  words  of  Christ,  "  If  ye  abide  in  my 
word  ...  ye  shall  know  the  truth,  and  the  truth  shall  make 
you  free."  He  believed  in  the  presence  of  the  personal 
Piedeemer  in  the  Church,  and  in  His  power  to  lead  it  onward 
and  upward  towards  perfection. 

This  faith  in  the  personal  Christ  is  the  keynote,  moreover, 
of  his  theological  thought  and  effort.  When  Strauss  in  1835 
issued  his  Life,  of  Jesus,  in  which  he  sought  to  undermine 
Christianity  by  attacking  the  genuineness  and  credibility  of 
its  records,  Dorner  in  the  same  year  began  the  publication  of 
his  great  work,  the  History  of  the  Dcvclop^ncnt  of  the  Doctrine 
of  the  Person  of  Christ  (completed  in  its  second  and  greatly 
enlarged  edition  in  1856),  which  aimed  to  show  that,  the 
primitive  Church  being  both  the  product  and   the  portrayer 


translator's  preface.  xi 

of  the  person  and  work  of  Jesus,  its  foundations  are  secure 
against  being  shaken  by  any  criticism  of  the  details  of  the 
written  record.  "  Dorner's  theological  labours,"  says  Prof, 
von  der  Goltz,  in  an  address  commemorative  of  Dorner  and 
of  Dorner's  friend  and  associate,  Emil  Herrmann,  "  had  from 
the  outset  two  fixed  starting-points,  closely  connected  with 
one  another  in  the  idea  of  personality — the  theanthropic 
person  of  Christ  and  justifying  faith.  Christ  the  centre  of 
piety,  Christ  the  Head  that  animates  the  Church,  Christ  the 
centre  of  the  creation  of  God  and  of  the  world's  history, 
Christ  the  second  Adam,  as  the  essential  and  perfect  vehicle 
of  God's  condescending  holy  love  to  men,  but  also  as  the 
prototype  of  a  permanent  humanity  destined  for  fellowship 
with  God  and  transfiguration  in  God ;  this,  on  the  one  hand, 
and,  on  the  other,  justifying  faith,  as  the  source  not  only  of 
the  doctrine,  but  also  of  the  life,  of  the  Evangelical  Church  ; 
justifying  faith,  as  requiring  and  finding  the  authority  of 
God's  word  which  testifies  of  Christ,  and  as  constituting  the 
perennial  source,  whence  is  derived  the  freedom  and  the 
dignity  of  the  Christian,  the  renewal  and  sanctification  of 
man,  and  the  animation  of  all  civilised  life  through  the 
divine  forces  that  sustain  and  train  it — these  were  the  two 
poles  between  which  Dorner's  research  and  production  moved." 
His  motto  was  Col.  ii.  3,  "  Christ,  in  whom  are  hid  all  the 
treasures  of  wisdom  and  knowledge."  To  unfold  those 
treasures,  all  the  energies  of  his  mind  and  all  the  intensity 
of  his  moral  nature  were  devoted.  He  believed  in  the  power 
of  the  human  soul  to  grasp  speculatively  much  of  the  wealth 
of  divine  truth.  He  had  no  sympathy  with  the  pseudo- 
modesty  of  those  who  affect  to  despise  metaphysical  specula- 
tion, and  to  trace  only  the  historical  development  of  human 
belief.  He  held  that  the  intellect  and  the  conscience  are, 
both  of  them,  real  sources  of  the  cognition  of  truth.  But  he 
did  not  therefore  hold  that  we  are  independent  of  history. 
It  was  not  a  merely  ideal,  but  the  historical,  Christ,  who 
formed  the  centre  and  inspiration  of  his  thought.  And  though 
sometimes  in  his  speculations  he  may  have  seemed  to  take 
too  daring  flights,  yet  he  was  not  seeking  thus  to  penetrate 
absolutely  new  realms  of  knowledge,  but  rather  to  make  more 
intelligible  and  impressive,  both  to  himself  and  others,  the 


XU  TRANSLATOR  S  PREFACE. 

immutable  truths  of  God's  revelation  of  Himself,  both  the 
natural  and  the  supernatural.  In  the  combination  of  meta- 
physical subtlety  with  intense  spirituality  he  was  a  second 
Augustine.  His  theology  was  a  part  of  his  religion.  In  all  his 
speculations  his  heart  was  more  deeply  interested  than  his  head. 
It  is,  therefore,  quite  intelligible  that  Dorner's  lectures  on 
Christian  Ethics  should  have  been  those  that  were  listened  to 
with  the  greatest  interest.  It  was  in  the  discussion  of  this 
theme  that  he  treated  what  was  nearest  his  own  heart. 
Christian  life  was  to  him  the  best  part  of  Christian  theology. 
Had  he  been  able  to  elaborate  the  whole  work  for  the  press, 
it  would  undoubtedly  have  exhibited  more  perfectly  his  own 
conception  of  the  foundation  and  development  of  morals. 
But  even  without  this  advantage  the  book  will  be  welcomed 
by  Dorner's  many  friends  and  admirers,  not  only  as  his  last 
published  treatise,  but  on  account  of  its  own  intrinsic  merits. 
It  is  not  necessary  here  to  characterize  the  work  in  detail. 
It  speaks  for  itself.  As  might  be  anticipated,  neither  the 
empirical  nor  the  utilitarian  theory  of  morals  receives  any 
support  from  the  author.  In  spite  of  the  loud-mouthed  claims 
of  materialistic  and  semi-materialistic  writers,  that  the  d  i^riori 
and  intuitional  methods  are  obsolete,  it  will  have  to  be  con- 
fessed by  any  one  who  carefully  reads  this  treatise  that  the  last 
word  has  not  yet  been  uttered. 

But  little  need  be  said  respecting  the  translation  of  the 
Christian  Ethics.  There  would  doubtless  have  been  a  greater 
uniformity  of  style,  could  a  single  translator  have  done  the 
whole  work ;  but  it  is  to  be  hoped  that  in  this  respect  the 
reader  will  find  no  marked  difference.  The  translators  have 
aimed  to  reproduce  the  thought  in  as  literal  a  translation  as 
regard  for  idiomatic  English  would  allow.  In  some  cases  it 
has  been  impossible,  without  unpardonable  freedom,  to  avoid 
]  ill  rases  which  will  have  a  somewhat  foreign  and  obscure 
sound ;  but  in  such  cases  the  connection  will,  it  is  hoped, 
always  sufficiently  elucidate  the  sense.  Dorner's  style,  as  his 
translators  have  always  found,  is  anything  but  easy  to  trans- 
late. But  this  does  not  imply  want  of  clearness  in  the 
original.  What  to  a  Cerman,  especially  one  versed  in  the 
schools  of  thought   in   which  I>oiner  was  trained,  would  be 


TKANSLATOUS  PREFACE.  xiii 

quite  simple  and  intelligible,  may  sometimes  seem,  especially 
in  a  slavishly  literal  translation,  to  be  little  better  than 
nonsense.  But  in  such  cases  the  fault  is  not  that  of  the 
original  author,  but  rather  that  of  the  translator  himself, 
whose  business  it  is  first  to  understand  the  original  and  then 
to  make  it  intelligible  in  the  translation.  If  the  Christian 
Ethics,  in  its  English  dress,  does  not  meet  this  requirement, 
the  translators  will  not  undertake  to  evade  their  personal 
responsibility,  but  will  be  thankful  for  kindly  criticism. 

The  first  part  of  the  book,  as  far  as  p.  224,  has  been 
translated  by  the  undersigned,  the  remainder  by  Eev.  Mr. 
Cunningham.-^  The  notes  and  additions  by  the  translators  are 
enclosed  in  square  brackets.  As  the  editor's  notes  are  like- 
wise thus  designated,  those  of  the  translators  are  further 
marked  by  the  addition  of  "  Tr.,"  except  in  cases  where  they 
would  be  readily  recognised  without  this  mark.  The  addi- 
tions in  the  earlier  part  of  the  English  translation  consist 
chiefly  in  an  enlargement  of  the  lists  of  books  given  by  the 
author  and  editor.  It  has  been  attempted,  so  far  as  possible, 
to  ascertain  which  of  the  foreign  works  have  been  translated 
into  English,  and  to  give  the  titles  of  the  translations.  Also, 
a  considerable  number  of  English  and  American  works  have 
been  inserted  in  the  lists.  Besides  these  additions,  which  are 
designated  by  the  brackets,  many  minor  emendations,  which 
could  not  conveniently  be  thus  marked,  have  been  made  in 
the  titles  and  date  of  publication  of  the  books  found  in  the 
German  original.  It  has  been  impossible,  in  the  time  and 
with  the  means  at  command,  to  attempt  anything  like  com- 
pleteness or  perfect  accuracy  in  these  additions.  But  it  is 
hoped  that  what  has  been  done  will  in  some  degree  enhance 
the  value  of  the  book,  the  labour  on  which,  much  greater  than 
was  anticipated,  has  been  lightened  by  personal  affection  and 

reverence  for  the  lamented  author. 

C.  M.  MEAD. 

Berlin,  1886. 

^  The  Publisliers  consider  it  riglit  to  state  that,  owing  to  temporary 
indisposition,  Mr.  Cunningham  was  nnable  to  revise  his  ]\IS.  This  work, 
together  with  the  revision  of  the  proof-sheets  and  the  completion  of  several 
gaps  iu  the  translation,  has,  however,  kindly  been  undertaken  by  Miss  Sophia 
Taylor  (translator  of  Luthardt's  Apolo'jctk  Lcclurcv,  Schiirer's  yew  Testament 
Times,  etc.)- 


EDITOR'S  PREFACE. 


In  editing  I.  A.  Dornev's  Christian  Etldcs  I  fulfil  &  duty 
laid  upon  me  by  the  autlior's  death — a  duty  which  I  under- 
took the  more  willingly,  as  the  lamented  author  had  com- 
missioned me  to  do  the  work  in  case  of  his  decease.  Dorner 
had  intended  to  publish  his  Mhics,  and  a  copy  dictated  by 
him,  extending  from  p.  1  to  p.  264,  was  finished,  as  also  an 
older  dictated  copy  which,  with  a  few  breaks,  extended  from 
p.  275  to  p.  463  (German  ed.).  In  these  portions  I  have  made 
only  slight  editorial  alterations,  where  the  copy,  which  could  not 
be  revised  by  the  author,  contained  errors  or  infelicities ;  and 
in  doing  so  I  have  always  followed  the  manuscripts  of  the 
lectures  as  they  lay  before  me.  The  remaining  part  of  the 
work  I  have  taken  from  Dorner's  lecture  notes,  making  the 
lectures  of  1879  the  basis,  yet  not  excluding  additions  from 
previous  lectures.  I  have  always  confined  myself  to  the 
language  of  the  text  before  me ;  and  where  I  deemed  it 
necessary  to  interpolate  anything  for  the  sake  of  perspicuity 
(which  was  seldom  the  case),  I  have  indicated  the  additions 
by  square  brackets,  and  generally  put  them  in  the  form  of 
footnotes.  The  principal  additions  belong  to  the  department 
of  references  to  books,  the  author  not  having  reached  the 
point  of  completing  this  part  for  the  press. 

The  Mhics  forms  an  indispensable  companion  piece  to  the 
Dogmatics  in  Dorner's  system ;  and  I  hope  that  the  publica- 
tion of  it  will  give  satisfaction  to  the  theological  public, 
inasmuch  as  the  lectures  on  ethics  were  among  the  most 
favourite  ones  delivered  by  Dorner,  May  the  defects  which 
inevitably  attach  to  a  posthumous  work  be  concealed  by  the 
wealth  of  thought,  and  by  the  originality  in  the  construction 
of  the  ethical  system,  which  the  work  presents. 

The  Editor,  A.  DORNER. 
Wittenberg,  Jiuie  20,  1885. 


TABLE  OF  CONTENTS. 


INTRODUCTIOK 

§  PAGE 

1.  Relation  of  Christian  Ethics  to  Faith  and  to  Dogmatics,      .             .  1 

2.  Meaning  of  Morality,              ......  6 

3.  Relation  of  Theological  or  Christian  Ethics  to  Philoso[iliical  Ethics,  17 

4.  Method, 42 

SYSTEM  OF  ETHICS. 

5.  Syllabus, 48 

.4.— STAETING-POINT. 

6.  Connection  between  Morality  in  general  and  the  Idea  of  God,           .  58 

7.  The  Nature  of  Morality,  primarily  in  God,    ....  68 

8.  Transition  to  the  World,        ......  !'3 

9.  God's  Ideal  of  the  Ethical  "World  in  general,              ...  06 


^.—SYSTEM. 

FIRST    PART. 

FOUNDATION. 

FUNDAMENTAL   DOCTKIKE.      THE   PREEEQISITES   AND   TKELIMINARY   STAGES  OF 
CIULISTIAN    MOr.AMTY. 

9a.   Syllabus,         ........         112 

FIEST  DIVISION. 

THE  OKDER  OF  THE  WORLD  AS  FIXED  BY  GOD  AT  CREATION,  ANTECEDENT  TO 
THE  MORAL  PROCESS.  V^/\ 

FIRST  SECTIOK 

THAT   'WHICH    IS    COMMON   TO   ALL   MEN    IN   THE    MORAL   FACULTIES   WITH 
WHICH   THEY   ARE    ENDOWED. 

CHArTER  FIRST. 
10,   Man's  Natural  or  Physical  Endowment  by  Creation,  .  .        113 

16 


XVI  CONTENTS. 

CHAPTER  SECOND. 


PAOK 


11.  The  Psychical  Elciur-ut  in  Man's  floral  Constitution,  ii  respective 

as  yet  of  Reason.         ......  122 

CHAPTER  THIRD. 

12.  Tlie  Rational  Element  in  the  Mo'-al  Constitution,  .  .         134 

SECOND  SECTION. 

INDIVIDUALITY    IN'   MAn's    MORAL   EXDOWMKXT. 

13.  On  the  Nature  of  Individuality,  .....         141 

14.  The  Actual  Genesis  of  the  chief  kinds  of  Individuality,  .  .         149 
lib.  Continuation.     The  TemperanK nts,         .             .             .             .         1.'35 

15.  The  Races  and  Nationalities,         ,             .             .             .             .162 
IG.  The  Talents, 174 

THIRD  SECTION. 

THE    I>IM?:i)!ATK   OR   NATURAL   UNION   OF   THE   DIFFERENCES    IN    HUMAN 
NATURE. 

17.  Civilisation  as  originating  in  a  natural  Growth,  .  .  .177 

18.  The  Delects  of  the  Civilisation  which  springs  up  by  Natuie,       .         183 

SECOND  DIVISION. 

THE    DIVINE    ORDER    OF    THE    UNIVERSE    AS    THE    LAW    OF    ACTION    FOR    THE 
WUR\L    FACULTIES;     OR    THE    FORMAL    MORAL    PUOCESS. 

19.  Synopsis,  ........         191 

FIRST  SECTIOX. 

THE    RINDING   (UIARACTER   OF   THE   OBJECTIVE   LAW. 

20.  The  ]Moral  Law  grounded  in  God.     Its  Fundamental  Features,  .         196 

21.  The  Denial  of  the  Formal  Fundamental  Attributes  of  the  Moral 

Law,      ........         202 

22.  Oneness  of  the  ^Moial  Law,  and  the  Conflict  of  Duties,    .  .         213 

23.  Duty  and  Right,  .......         221 

SECOND  SECTION. 

THE   DOCTRINE   OF   CONSCIENCE. 


[  The  Nature  and  Significance  of  Conscience,        .  .  .         225 


24. 
24a. 

25.  Degrees  of  Conscience,       .  .  .  .  .  ,237 

26.  Historical  Forms  of  Conscience,    .....         248 


THIRD  SECTION. 

THE   DOCTRINE    OF   FRKUJuM. 

27  29.  The  Historical  Forms  of  the  Antithesis  of  Determinism  and  In- 

determinism,     .......  253 

27.  Absolute  Physical  Determinism,  and  Absolute  Indcterminisni,   .  25:; 

28.  Phvsieal  Determinism  and  Determinism  of  IndilTcrence,  .  2ii0 


CONTENTS.  XVil 

§  PAGK 

2ti.  Theological  PriHletenniuism.  The  Doctrine  of  Absolv\te  Piedcs- 
tination  and  Predeterminism  of  Freedom.  Freedom,  as  the 
Transcendental  Freedom  of  an  Intellectual  Existence,    ,  .         2G6 

30.  Positive  Doctrine  of  Freedom,  .....         273 

THIED  DIVISION. 

THE    MOr.AL    OKDEU   OF   THE   WORLD   AS   THE   PRACTICAL   GOAL   OF   THE 
MOVEMENT   OF   THE   MORAL    PROCESS. 

31.  The  Contents  of  the  Moral  Ideal,    .  ....         283 

32.  The  Way  to  the  Realization  of  this  Ideal,    .  .  .  .298 

FIRST  SECTION. 

ADVANCE   FROM    THE    EUD^MONISTIC    STAGE   TO   THE   STAGE    OF   LAW,    OR   OF 

RIGHT. 

33.  The  Absolnte  Sphere  of  Right  (Relation  between  God  and  Man),    .         301 
33a.  The  Secondary  Sphere  of  Right,      .....         303 

SECOND  SECTION 

THE    IMPERFECTION   OF   THE   STAGE   OF   LAW   OR   OF    RIGHT. 

CHAPTER  FIRST. 

Its    IMPERFECTION   APART   FROM   SIX. 

34.  Its  Imperfection  in  the  Absolute  Sphere,     ....         311 
31a.   Its  Imperfection  in  the  Secondary  Sphere,  ....         313 

CHAPTER  SECOXD. 

35.  The  Stage  of  Right  with  reference  to  Evil,  .  .  .  .316 
Note,             ........         320 

35a.  The  Actual  Existence  of  Sin  in  Hnmauity,  .  .  .         320 

356.  The  Historical  Counteraction  of  Good  against  Evil,  and  the  Pre- 
paration for  the  Principle  of  Christian  Morality,  .  .         325 

THIRD  SECTION. 

'iHE   STAGE   OF    LOVE    OR   OF   THE   GOSPEL   AS   ESSENTIALLY   THE    ETHICAL   GOAL 
OF   THE   WORLD. 

36.  The  Necessity  of  the  Stage  of  Love,  by  means  of  a  Revelation  on 

the  part  of  God,   .......         332 

37.  The  Necessity  of  the  God-man  from  Ethical  Points  of  View,  .         334 


SECOND  PART. 

THE  GOOD  AS  REALIZED  IN  CHRISTIANITY. 

38.  Syllabus,       ........         343 

FIEST  DIVISION. 

CHRIST   THE  GOD-MAX,    AS   THE    REALIZATION,    IN    PRINCIPLE,    OF    MORALITY    IX 
MANKIND.       ETHICAL   CURISTOLOGY. 

39.  Summary,     ........         343 


xviil  CONTENTS. 

ft 

FIRST  SECTION. 
Christ  the  peufect  kevelation  of  the  law. 

§  PAQK 

40.  Christ  the  Kevelation  of  the  Law,    .  .  .  .  .         344 

SECOND  SECTION. 

CHRIST   THE   ALL-EMBRACING   VIRTUE   AND   THE    MAN    WHO   RENDERS 
COMPLETE   SATISFACTION   TO    GOD. 

41.  Christ  tlie  all-embracing  Virtue,      .....         348 

THIRD  SECTION. 

CHRIST   AS   THE   PRINCIPLE   OF   THE    KINGDOM    OF    GOD    AND   THE   HEAD   OF 
HUMANITY. 

42.  Christ  the  Principle  of  the  Kingdom  of  God  (of  the  Highest  Good),       351 


SECOND  DIVISION". 

CHRISTIAN   VIRTUE   AS   EXHIBITED    IN   THE   INDIVIDUAL. 

43.  Introduction,  .......         355 

43a.  Syllabus,      ........         363 

FIRST  SECTION. 

THE    GENESIS   OF   THE    CHRISTIAN    CHARACTER, 

CHAPTER  FIRST. 

44.  Faith,  ........         364 

CHAPTER  SECOND. 

45.  Love, 372 

CHAPTER  THIRD. 

CHRISTIAN   WISDOM. 

4G.  Christian  Wisdom,  .......         382 

47.  The  Christian  View  of  the  World,   .....         388 

SECOND  SECTION. 

THE   SUBSISTENCE   OF   THE   CHRISTIAN   CHARACTER   BY    MEANS   OF   CONSTANT 
RENEWAL   AND    EXERCISE. 

48.  The  Subsistence  of  the  Christian  Character,  Fidelity,  Stedfastnesa, 

Sobriety — Ascetics,  .  .  .  .  .  .40] 

THIRD  SECTION. 

THE   SELF-MANIFESTATION    OR   SELF-DEVELOPMENT   OF   THE   CHRISTIAM 
CHARACTER. 

49.  Synopsis,      ........        412 


CONTENTS.  XIX 

CHAPTER  FIRST. 

THE    SELF-DEVELOPMENT   OB"   THE   CHRISTTAN   CilAllACTER    IN    ITS    ABSOLUTE 

llELATIONS. 
§  PAOE 

50.  Christian  Piety  in  itself,       ......         413 

51.  Christian  Piety  as  Inward  Activity  in  Contemplation  and  Prayer,  416 

52.  Contemplation,         .  .  .  .  .  .  .417 

63.  Prayer,  ........         422 

54.  Times  of  Prayer  and  Contemplation,  or  the  Order  of  Life  determined 

by  Christian  Piety,  ......         430 

55.  Christian  Religious  Zeal,      ......         441 


CHAPTER  SECOND. 

THE   NEW   PERSONALITY,    CREATED    IN   THE    IMAGE   OF   GOD,    IN    RELATION 
TO    ITSELF. 

56.  Christian  Self-love  ;  the  necessary  Grounds  on  which  it  rests,        .  445 

57.  Christian  Self-love  ;  its  Nature  in  general,               .             .             .  449 

58.  Christian  Self-love;  its  special  characteristics  both  in  itself  and 

with  regard  to  Otiiers,      ......  452 

I.  Care  lor  Personal  Worth  and  Well-being,            .             .             .  452 
Survey,         ........  452 

1.  Care  of  the  Physical  Life,        .....  452 

59.  Care  of  our  Physical  Existence,        .....  452 
59a.  Duelling,    ........  454 

60.  Care  of  the  Body,     .......  456 

61.  Attention  to  Virtuous  Happiness,    .....  458 

62.  Attention  to  Virtuous  Purity  and  Beauty,  ....  464 

63.  Virtuous  Ownership,             ......  469 

2.  Christian  Self-love  with  respect  to  the  Spirit,             .             .  4S0 

64.  Virtuous  Refinement  and  Stability  of  Character,     .             .             .  480 

II.  Christian  Self-love  as  Self-affirmation  and  Self-manift-station 

with  reference  to  Others,         .....  484 

65.  Survey.     (Personal  Dignity  shown  in  Independence  of  Character, 

in  maintaining  our  Good  Name  and  our  legitimate  Personal 
Influence  by  means  of  Truthfulness,  and  in  the  Choice  and 

Exercise  of  a  Vocation),             .....  484 

66.  Truthfulness,            .......  487 

67.  Oaths,            ........  492 

68.  Vocation,      ........  498 

CHAPTER  THIRD. 

THE   CHRISTIAN    IX   RELATION   TO   OTHERS,    CHRISTIAN   SOCIAL    LOVE. 

69.  Christian  Social  Love,          ......  504 

70.  Social  Intercourse,    .  .  ,  .  ,  .  .514 


THIKD  DIVISION. 

rilE    ORGANIZED   "WORLD    OF    CHRISTIAN    MORALITY,    THE    MORAL    COMMUNITIES 
IN   THE    KINGDOM    OF    GOD. 

71.   Synopsis,     ........         516 


XX  CONTENTS. 

FIRST  SECTION. 

THE    (natural)    FUXDAMKNTAL   MORAL   COMMUNITY,    OR    THE    nOUSEHOLD. 

CHAPTER  FIRST. 
§  r  voz 

72.  JManiage,      ........         522 

CHAPTER  SECOND. 

73.  The  Family,  .......         549 

CHAPTER  THIRD. 

74.  Extension  of  the  Household  by  means  of  Friends  and  Servants,     .         552 

SECOXD  SECTION. 

TITE   SPECIAL   MORAL   COMMUNITIES   THAT   ARE   THE   PRODUCT   OF    REFLECTION 
OR   OF   HUMAN    ART. 

CHAPTER  FIRST. 

THE   STATE. 

75.  Ideaof  the  Stale,     .......  554 

76.  Antithesis  of  Rnlers  and  Sulijects,  .  ....  562 

77.  The  Constitution,     .......  568 

78.  Relation  of  the  State  to  its  Future  and  to  other  States,       .  .  578 

CHAPTER  SECOND. 

79.  Art, 581 

CHAPTER  THIRD. 

80.  Science,        ........        587 

THIRD  SECTION. 

THE    ABSOLUTE   SPHERE,    THE  RELIGIOUS   COMMUNITY. 

81.  Ideaof  the  Church,  ......         591 

82.  Cardinal  Functions  of  the  Church,  .....         598 

83.  Ecclesiastical  Organization,  .....        604 


SYSTEM  OF  CHRISTIAN"  ETHICS. 


INTRODUCTION. 

§1. 

CnrJSTiAN  Morals  or  Ethics  is  the  second  main  division  of 
Thetic  [Positive]  Theology.  As  such  it  has,  in  common 
with  Dogmatics,  its  source  in  Faith,  which  involves  an 
immediate  knowledge  not  only  of  God  and  of  His  acts, 
but  also  of  man  and  of  his  relation  to  God  and  to  the 
divine  will. 

1.  The  relation  of  systematic  theology  to  the  other  depart- 
ments of  theology  has  been  pointed  out  in  detail  by  me  in 
another  work.^  The  peculiarity  of  systematic  theology  lies  in 
this,  that  it  and  it  alone  has  for  its  province  to  exhibit  and  to 
establish  Christian  truth  as  truth.  Tliereby  it  answers  to  an 
essential  need  of  the  soul,  and  to  the  inmost  tendency  of 
Christianity  as  proceeding  out  of  the  self-revelation  of  Qxod. 
When  faith  has  accepted  Christianity,  it  receives,  indeed,  at 
the  outset  as  its  reward  the  satisfaction  of  a  son  who  has 
found  again  the  lost  house  of  his  father.  The  believer  knovv's 
also,  in  a  certain  sense,  what  or  on  whom  he  believes ;  and 
that  which  Christianity  contains,  answering  truly  to  his  needs, 
works  out  its  quiet,  healing,  illuminating  effect.  But  the 
spirit  of  the  faith  which  desires  to  grow  up  to  manhood  does 
not  stop  short  with  knowing  on  whom  it  believes.  It  desires 
to  know  also  why  it  believes  with  a  good  conscience,  and 
Avith  the  stedfasuness  and  fidelity  which,  through  the  appre- 
hension of  the  intrinsic  truth  of  what  is  believed,  assumes 
'  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  i.  pp.  21-24. 
A 


2  §  1.    DELATION  or  ETHICS  TO  FAITH  AND  DOGMATICS. 

the  form  of  duty  and  of  a  self-assured,  joyful  aspiration. 
Only  when  one  has  recognised  that  the  Christianity  delivered 
to  him  is  the  truth,  which  nothing  in  heaven  or  on  earth  can 
contradict,  is  he  able  properly  to  give  an  answer  (1  Pet. 
iii.  15)  against  doubts,  whether  coming  from  within  or  from' 
without ;  only  from  the  recognition  of  Christian  truth  as  truth 
comes  also  the  living  impulse  to  champion  victoriously  the 
sovereignty  of  Christian  truth.  For  the  truth  must  lay  claim 
not  merely  to  be  valid  as  truth  for  this  or  that  individual,  but 
to  find  due  recognition  with  all  rational  beings  ;  and  from  this 
it  is  plain  why  the  Christian  knowledge,  so  highly  commended 
in  the  New  Testament,  is  of  the  greatest  importance  for  the 
practical  life  of  individuals  and  of  the  Church.  Only  thus 
does  Christianity  do  justice  to  itself  as  the  divine  revelation. 
Before  the  Christian  revelation  God  poured  out  upon  mankind 
a  wealth  of  valuable  knowledge,  and  even  foretold  the  con- 
summation of  religion.  ISTevertheless  before  the  Christian  era 
men  were  not  yet  in  the  position  of  children  of  God,  but  still 
in  the  position  of  servants  (Gal.  iv.  1).  But  it  is  the  cha- 
racteristic of  the  servant  not  to  know  what  the  master  does 
(John  XV.  15).  He  learns  indeed  the  master's  will,  and  if  he 
be  a  faithful  servant  he  puts  confidence  in  the  master's  word 
as  wise  and  good ;  but  the  servant  as  such  has  no  insight  into 
the  goodness  and  wisdom  of  the  divine  utterances.  Tor  this 
reason,  as  the  later  books  of  the  Old  Testament  show,  he  lacks 
also  the  power  to  encounter  arising  doubts  victoriously,  and 
not  through  mere  resignation,  such  as  is  required,  e.g.,  in 
Ecclesiastes  and  in  the  Book  of  Job.  It  is  true  that  mere 
resignation  is  a  waiting  for  the  future  solution  of  the  doubts 
and  perplexities  of  thought;  it  is  strictly,  however,  no  real 
progress  towards  a  more  and  more  comprehensive,  harmonious 
view  of  the  world,  but  is  at  best  only  an  exercise  in  humble 
and  quiet  stcdfastness  in  a  position  already  reached,  yet  still 
imperfect. 

2.  Systematic  theology,  like  theology  in  general,  presup- 
poses experience,  outward,  and  especially  inward,  or  faith  ;  for 
faith  brings  Christian  experience.^ 

Faith  is,  first,  the  eye,  or  the  faculty,  which  takes  Christian 
truths  and  facts  into  the  mind ;  but  it  likewise  includes  in 
1  Cf.  my  System  of  Christian  Dodrine,  vol.  i.  pp.  17-21. 


FAITH  THE  SOUKCE  OF  ETHICS  AND  DOGMATICS.  3 

itself  these  Christian  objects  in  such  a  way  that  it  delivers 
them  over  to  philosophic  thought  and  apprehension,  to  be 
elaborated  and  further  appropriated.  For  it  itself  has  an 
impulse  not  merely  to  get  possession  of  the  truth,  i.e.  of 
Christianity,  but  also  to  become  conscious  and  sure  of  the 
truth  as  truth,  to  which  end  science  also  essentially  con- 
tributes (2  Tim.  i.  12;  1  Pet.  iii.  15).  Where  faith  is  there 
is  a  Christian  person,  to  whom  is  presented  a  world  of  things 
on  which  his  powers  of  cognition  and  of  volition  are  to  be 
exercised.  Accordingly  it  might  seem  plausible,  dogmatics 
and  ethics  being  derived  from  faith  as  a  higher  unity,  so  to 
view  faith  as  their  common  source,  that  dogmatics  should 
be  looked  upon  as  theoretical  theology,  ethics  as  practical 
theology ;  but  this  view  would  do  justice  to  neither  the  one 
nor  the  other.  For  ethics  no  less  than  dogmatics  must 
present  a  theory,  a  system  of  knowledge ;  dogmatics,  on  the 
other  hand,  could  not  be  satisfied  with  being  directed  merely 
by  theoretical  considerations.  The  difference  between  them, 
while  they  in  common  claim  to  be  sciences,  lies  rather  in 
their  subject-matter. 

Schleiermacher^  says  that  the  Christian  life  is,  on  the  one 
hand,  one  of  repose,  and  as  such  is  the  subject  of  Christian 
doctrine ;  that,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  a  life  of  activity, 
and  as  such  is  to  be  described  by  Christian  ethics.  But  to 
say  nothing  of  the  fact  that  on  this  view  there  would  result 
only  a  quantitative  and  therefore  fluctuating  difference  between 
the  two,  it  is  plain  that  since  both  would  be  only  mutually 
supplementary  descriptions  of  a  pious  Christian's  state  of 
mind,  they  would  treat  merely  of  that  which  is  human  and 
subjective.  Nay,  since  piety  is  something  ethical,  a  virtue, 
we  do  not  get  beyond  the  realm  of  mere  ethics.  And  the 
case  is  similar  with  Nitzsch,  who,  in  his  System  of  Christian 
Doctrine,  goes  on  to  treat  of  dogmatics  and  ethics  as  a  single 
science.  Nitzsch  says  the  Christian  personality  is  a  totality, 
a  solid  unity,  and  that  therefore  th^  completest  form  of 
dogmatic  and  of  ethical  science  is  the  presentation  of  the 
one  Christian  life  in  its  fulness,  that  is,  the  treatment  of 
dogmatics  and  ethics  rather  as  one  M  ence,  inasmuch  as  in 
Christianity   the    religious    and    the    moral    are    inseparably 

1  Christl.  Sine,  pp.  12-24. 


4  §  1.    EELATIOX  OF  ETHICS  TO  FAITH  AND  DOGMATICS. 

connected  and  are  meant  to  permeate  each  other.  But  if 
the  task  were  merely  to  present  the  higher  Christian  life  in 
its  unity,  of  coarse,  therefore,  according  to  its  religious  and 
moral  character,  there  would  remain,  strictly  speaking,  nothing 
hut  morality  to  be  treated ;  for  dogmatics  there  would  be  left 
no  special  ]3rovince.  Christian  personality  is  morally  com- 
plete only  in  so  far  as  it  includes  Christian  piety ;  but  in  that 
case  there  would  be  left  as  the  subject-matter  of  systematic 
theology  only  the  human  being,  the  Christian  person ;  about 
God  and  divine  acts  it  would  have  to  keep  silence.  This 
leads  to  the  correct  statement  of  the  relation  between 
dogmatics  and  ethics. 

3.  It  is  true  that  if  there  were  no  objective  knowledge  of 
God,  not  even  in  Christianity,  the  right  of  dogmatics  to  a 
special  existence  would  be  out  of  the  question.  But  it  is 
.only  in  the  most  modern  times  that  some  men  have  embraced 
such  a  doctrine  of  absolute  ignorance  of  God  Himself  and  His 
essence,  and  are  preparing  even  to  affirm  that  it  is  a  higher 
knowledge.  It  is  not  so  much  Kant's  critical  system  from 
which  such  a  doctrine  is  derived,  for  his  is  not  a  system  of 
scepticism ;  it  proceeds  rather  from  the  assumption,  imported 
from  France  and  England,  that  all  knowledge  is  derived 
merely  from  experience,  that  in  the  mind  there  is  no 
independent  source  of  knowledge.^  But  Christianity  rejects 
this  theory,  however  much  it  may  wrap  itself  in  the  garment 
of  a  self-chosen  humility.  According  to  Christianity,  it  is  the 
heathen  who  know  nothing  of  God ;  but  Christianity  has 
brought  a  revelation  from  God,  and  that  not  merely  concern- 
ing mankind ;  rather  the  new  disclosures  which  it  has  indeed 
brought  concerning  men,  their  nature,  and  their  destiny,  have 
their  ultimate  foundation  always  in  this,  that  it  brings  dis- 
closures concerning  God  and  concerning  divine  acts  which 
point  back  to  the  divine  essence.  If  this  is  certain  to  the 
Christian  mind,  then  we  have,  as  the  province  of  dogmatics, 
distinguishing  it  from  all  other  branches  of  learning,  and 
insuring  for  it  an  independent  position,  the  description  of 
God  and  His  acts.  If  this  is  so,  then  there  remains  as  the 
subject  of  ethics  in  general  the  normal,  i.e.  ethical,  life  of  the 

^  Reference  is  here  had  esiiecially  to  Auguste  Comte,  John  Stuart  Mill,  and 
Herbert  Spencer. 


ETHICS  A  EELATIVELY  INDEPENDENT  SCIENCE.  5 

human  creature.  The  ethical  has,  to  be  sure,  its  place  in 
dogmatics,  namely,  the  ethical  element  in  God,  a  knowledge 
of  which  presupposes  an  ethical  element  in  man.  Spinoza's 
ethics  is  an  ethics  of  God  and  of  the  creature.  But  on  the 
very  supposition  that  dogmatics,  as  it  ought,  treats  of  an 
ethical  conception  of  God,  and  accordingly  sets  forth  the 
ethical  element  in  God,  there  remains  to  ethics  in  distinction 
from  dogmatics  the  ethical  element  in  the  creature,  especially 
mankind,  as  its  peculiar  domain.  As  surely  as  God  and  the 
creature  are  different,  so  surely  are  dogmatics  and  ethics  to 
be  distinguished.  Thus,  moreover,  so  much  is  at  once  deter- 
mined concerning  the  relative  place  of  the  two  departments, 
that  so  surely  as  God  is  the  supreme  cause  upon  which 
everything  else  depends,  ethics  cannot  be  called  the  founda- 
tion of  dogmatics,  but  stands  to  dogmatics  in  a  relation  of 
dependence. 

But  this  does  not  mean  that  ethics  is  only  a  dependent 
appendage,  or  even  part,  of  systematic  theology.  Ethics, 
rather,  is  a  relatively  independent  department  standing  side 
by  side  with  dogmatics.  God's  creative  causality  is  not  ex- 
hausted when  it  has  made  a  dependent  thing  without  a  causality 
and  life  of  its  own.  In  that  case  there  would  be  only  God 
and  the  divine  act,  nothing  existent  but  this.  Eather,  on  the 
other  hand,  the  will  and  the  aim  of  the  creative  activity  of 
God  is  the  production  of  life  in  His  creatures,  especially  in 
intelligent  creatures — a  life  having  its  own  independent  action. 
This  is  implied  in  the  fact  that  there  is  no  creative  act  of 
God  which  does  not  pass  over  into  preservation,  that  is,  into 
the  realm  in  which  there  is  room  for  secondary  causality. 
The  delineation,  however,  of  that  human  causality,  which 
merits  the  name  of  ethico-Christian,  presupposes  not  merely 
some  one  single  dogma,  but  God  and  the  totality  of  His  acts, 
i.e.  the  whole  of  systematic  theology ;  so  that  for  this  reason 
also  ethics  is  a  science  different  from  dogmatics  and  relatively 
independent.  On  this  point,  too,  we  should  not  be  confused 
by  the  circumstance  that  certain  doctrines  indeed,  as  that  of 
sin,  of  regeneration,  of  sanctification,  and  of  the  Church, 
demand  a  place  in  both  departments,  for  they  occur  in  them 
under  different  aspects — in  dogmatics,  under  that  of  divine 
activity,  of  their  relation  to  the  divine   decree,  and  of   the 


6      .  §2.    THE  MEANING  OF  MORALITY. 

realization  of  the  decree ;  in  the  science  of  morals,  under  the 
aspect  of  human  activity. 

4.  In  the  foregoing  the  province  in  general  is  indicated 
into  which  our  science  falls.  But  since  the  activity  of  human 
life  is  very  manifold,  the  question  arises  whether  everything 
and  anything  which  can  be  called  a  human  function  belongs 
to  our  science,  or  whether  only  a  narrower  circle  of  human 
activity  is  to  be  reserved  for  it.  The  word  moral,  it  is  true, 
is  used  in  a  wider  sense,  embracing  both  the  morally  normal 
and  the  morally  abnormal.  But  ethics,  as  will  soon  be  more 
clearly  shown,  has  primarily  to  do  with  the  normal  or  the 
good.  But,  in  the  next  place,  the  word  moral,  even  in  the 
wider  sense,  is  not  applicable  to  every  kind  of  human  activity. 
There  is  a  multitude  of  conditions  and  functions  to  which  the 
idea  of  morality  is  applicable  in  neither  a  good  nor  a  bad 
sense  ;  therefore  we  must  advance  to  a  stricter  definition  of 
the  subject  of  our  science. 

§  2.    The  Meaning  of  Morality. 

The  subject  of  Christian  ethics  is,  in  the  first  instance,  the 
morally  good,  or  the  absolutely  vjorthy,  as  existing  for  the 
human  personal  luill,  and  as  attaining  reality  through  it, 
i.e.  by  means  of  the  self-determination  of  the  will.  As 
the  absolutely  worthy,  the  ethical  is  to  be  distinguished 
from  the  physical,  the  logical,  and  the  resthetical,  all  of 
which,  although  it  cannot  be  denied  that  they  have  a 
peculiar  worth  and  even  a  certain  necessity,  yet,  in 
comparison  with  the  ethical,  have  only  a  mediate, 
secondary  importance.  But  in  the  idea  of  the  good, 
and  derivable  from  it  alone,  is  involved,  moreover, 
the  notion  of  evil  as  its  opposite ;  and  to  this  also  is 
applicable  the  notion  of  self  -  determination  of  the 
personal  will.  So  then  the  two,  the  morally  good  and 
the  morally  bad,  although  they  constitute  in  relation  to 
each  other  an  absolute  antithesis,  the  absolutely  worthy 
and  the  absolutely  worthless,  yet,  as  moral,  stand  sensu 
medio  opposed  to  the  physical. 


MORALITY  AS  THE  HIGHEST  GOOD.  7 

1.  In  order  to  attain  to  a  definite  conception  of  our  science, 
we  start  with  the  various  names  which  in  the  course  of 
centuries  have  been  coined  for  it ;  for  in  the  giving  of  names 
the  awakened  rational  instinct  is  accustomed  to  picture  forth 
the  essence  of  the  thing  to  which  it  has  been  devoting  its 
attention.  The  consideration  of  names  is  all  the  more 
instructive  when  they  express  various  conceptions  of  the 
object,  or  various  aspects  presented  by  it.  First  to  be 
considered  are  the  terms,  science  of  the  good,  of  duty,  and 
of  virtue, 

a.  As  to  the  first  name,  man,  as  a  teleological  being, 
endowed  with  a  power  to  judge  of  things  according  to  their 
worth,  asks,  so  soon  as  understanding  is  awakened,  what  end 
is  worth  striving  after  and  can  be  attained  by  effort.  Very 
many  things  present  themselves  as  possible ;  but  the  intelli- 
gent man  will  decide  in  favour  of  that  which  seems  to  him  to 
\)Q  the  greater  good,  i.e.  seems  to  be  most  in  harmony  with 
his  nature  and  inclinations.  So  it  is  natural  that  one  of  the 
oldest  forms  of  the  doctrine  of  morals  is  that  of  the  good,  or  of 
the  good  things  which  can  make  life  worth  living,  or  make  it 
happy,  and  to  which  human  action,  self-determination  in  doing 
and  leaving  undone,  should  conform.  There  are,  to  be  sure, 
peoples  to  whom  life  itself  appears  to  be  an  evil,as  the  Buddhists; 
but  even  these  have  a  doctrine  of  the  highest  good.  Their 
good  consists  in  being  delivered  from  this  evil  of  life,  by 
withdrawing  the  consciousness  and  will  from  the  multiplicity 
of  finite  things,  in  order,  after  these  have  both  been  subdued, 
to  attain  to  an  inactive  blessed  rest,  if  not  to  annihilation. 
With  the  West  -  Aryan  peoples,  and  especially  with  the 
Hebrews,  it  is  otherwise.  Since  they  look  upon  life  as  a 
good,  their  effort  is  directed  to  preserving  and  enriching  it  by 
means  of  well-ordered  consistent  action ;  for  these  races  have 
a  historic  sense.  With  them  moral  precepts  or  rules  have 
the  aim  so  to  regulate  life  that  it  shall  be  superior  to  all 
evils,  and  thus  become  more  and  more  worth  living.  It 
was  this  that  led  the  Greeks  and  Eomans  to  inquire  after  the 
arfaQov  or  Ka\oKa<^/a66v,  after  the  honum  or  summum  honum  ; 
and  in  like  manner  the  Hebrew  ^^^^^^  (wisdom)  promises 
life  through  the  knowledge  of  the  true  good  and  of  the  means 
of  attainino-  it. 


8  §  2,    THE  MEANING  OF  MOEALITY. 

But  the  word  honuni,  a<ya6ov,  like  our  "  good,"  or  like 
KaKov  and  malum,  is  ambiguous.  That  can  be  called  good 
which  is  agreeable  and  yields  pleasure.  It  can  also  mean  that 
which  is  in  itself  universally  and  absolutely  good.  If  good  is 
taken  in  the  first  sense,  then  a  doctrine  of  morals  having 
positive  contents,  and  being  valid  for  all  individuals  alike,  is 
not  possible,  since  the  difference  of  inclinations  and  of  needs 
in  different  individuals  is  endless,  and  since,  so  long  as  there 
is  no  law  universally  binding,  it  must  rest  with  the  judgment 
of  the  individual  to  determine  what  he  shall  look  upon  as  the 
pleasure  congenial  to  him,  or  as  the  damage  or  pain  to  be 
shunned.  Furthermore,  in  this  case  virtue  only  signifies  a 
means ;  it  is  only  the  ability  or  skill  to  unite  the  greatest 
possible  well-being  with  the  least  possible  evil.  But  most 
certainly  a  higher  conception  of  good  things  is  possible,  and 
especially  of  the  highest  good.  Even  Plato  and  Aristotle 
could  talk  of  a  good  which  has  ideal  wortli  and  import, — Plato 
especially,  even  of  an  a^aQov  which  is  connected  with  the 
oGiov.  They  find  the  highest  good  ideally  in  wisdom  or  in 
the  knowledge  of  truth  ;  they  find  it  really  in  the  State,  which, 
if  it  is  just  and  endued  with  all  virtues,  provides  for  each 
individual  that  which  is  best  and  due.  But  knowledge  in 
and  of  itself,  as  even  Aristotle  begins  to  see,  cannot  insure 
a  good  will,  or  virtue ;  it  is  an  erroneous  intellectual  con- 
ception of  Socrates  and  Plato,  that  knowledge  certainly 
determines  and  moves  the  will.  In  the  State,  however,  the 
chief  importance  attaches  to  the  outward  act,  the  overt 
work,  by  which  the  State  continually  renews  itself;  but  the 
disposition  and  the  moral  worth  of  the  individual  receive  in 
this  case  too  little  attention. 

A  higher  claim  to  constitute  the  highest  good  is  made  by  the 
Biblical  idea  of  the  kingdom  of  God,  which  indeed  bears  a  certain 
analogy  to  that  of  the  State  (as  is  indicated  in  the  phrase  civitas 
Dei),  but  contains  a  more  comprehensive  and  higher  meaning. 
And,  in  fact,  some  modern  moralists,  as  Schwartz  and  Hirscher, 
have  treated  ethics  as  the  doctrine  of  the  kingdom  of  God.  But 
certain  as  it  is,  that  objective  reality  belongs  to  morality  as  a 
whole,  yet  the  notion  of  the  kingdom  of  God  is  not  in  itself 
adequate  to  be  an  exhaustive  description  of  morality.  By  it 
one  essential  aspect  of  morality  is  expressed,  namely,  that  it  is 


MORALITY  AS  OBLIGATION.  9 

an  entity.  But  so  is  nature,  the  physical  world,  an  entity ; 
and  the  essence  of  morality  is  not  expressed  unless  at  the 
same  time  personality  and  its  self-activity  are  taken  into 
consideration.  In  the  notion  of  the  kingdom  of  God  in  and  of 
itself  the  notion  of  personality,  so  weighty  in  morals,  is  thrown 
too  much  into  the  background ;  and  yet  morality  must  have 
its  first  existence  in  the  person :  a  thing  does  not  first  become 
moral  by  means  of  society  or  the  kingdom  of  God. 

h.  Others  recognise  that  the  peculiarity  of  morality  does  not 
consist  in  its  simply  having  an  objective  being.  They  see 
rather  that  an  Onght  bearing  upon  the  will,  that  is,  the 
notion  of  duty,  or  the  moral  lav),  is  an  essential  characteristic 
of  morality.  The  Stoics  therefore  define  our  science  as  the 
eiricnrjixri  rSiv  KaOrjKovToiv ;  and  here  belongs  also  Kant's 
Categorical  Imperative,  upon  which  he  seeks  to  build  his 
doctrine  of  morals.  Does  now  this  definition  embrace  the 
whole  realm  over  which  ethical  science  must  lay  claim  ? 
Certainly  nothing  can  be  shown  to  be  moral  which  may  not  in 
some  way  be  or  become  duty  ;  the  whole  realm  of  morals  must 
be  brought  under  the  aspect  of  duty ;  and  this  is  accordingly 
an  essential  side  of  the  matter.  It  must  be  acknowledged,  too, 
that  in  the  very  notion  of  duty  personality  is  recognised ;  for 
this  notion  is  determined  by  personality  as  a  union  of  will  and 
understanding.  The  idea  of  duty  indeed,  although  it  itself 
represents  that  which  is  morally  necessary,  presupposes 
freedom,  self-determination ;  for  the  necessity  of  duty  is  quite 
another  necessity  than  that  of  compulsion  or  of  natural  law. 
The  law  which  is  involved  in  duty  is  not  characterized  by  the 
necessity  of  immediately  passing  over  into  actuality  so  soon 
as  it  is  present  to  the  soul ;  rather,  its  characteristic  is  the 
desire  to  become  actualized  through  free  self-determination. 
It  is  an  appeal  to  freedom ;  it  is  a  distinction  between  man 
and  all  merely  natural  creatures,  whereby  he  is  ennobled. 
And  something  so  lofty  lies  in  this  consciousness  of  freedom, 
that  there  are  attempts  at  ethical  systems  which  have  as  their 
leading  idea  merely  this  freedom,  the  self-determination  of 
free  personality ;  thus,  to  be  sure,  we  are  unawares  led  back 
again  to  a  sort  of  more  refined  utilitarianism,  and  that  which 
is  morally  necessary  is  not  secure  as  over  against  mere  caprice. 
Important  for  morality  as  self-determination  is,  yet  not  every- 


10  §  2.    THE  MEANING  OF  MORALITY. 

thing  whicli  proceeds  from  self-determination  can  be  therefore 
called  morally  good,  unless  the  word  moral  is  taken  scnsu 
Miibiguo.  To  be  sure,  as  no  definite  moral  element  is  involved 
in  the  mere  notion  of  freedom,  and  as  at  the  best,  if  the  self- 
assertion  of  freedom  is  conceived  to  be  morality,  only  the 
negative  requirement  can  be  made,  that  everything  impairing 
freedom  should  be  averted,  without  any  positive  moral  process 
taking  place ;  so  also  the  notion  of  duty  is  in  itself  only  a 
formal  one.  It  affirms  indeed  that  only  that  is  duty  which  is 
absolutely  obligatory ;  but  what  that  is  which  is  absolutely 
obligatory  is  not  evident  from  the  notion  of  duty  in  itself,  and 
can  also  not  be  derived  from  it.  Consequently  here,  too,  at 
the  best  we  reach  only  the  negative  result  of  excluding  what 
cannot  pass  as  moral,  and  is  therefore  to  be  avoided,  but  without 
knowing  any  the  better  what  is  to  be  regarded  as  really 
accordant  with  duty.  Furthermore,  the  notion  of  law 
represents  morality  in  the  sense  of  that  which  ought  to  he; 
but  the  mere  Ought  is  a  nonentity.  If,  therefore,  the 
whole  of  morality  were  included  in  law,  it  would  remain 
excluded  from  actuality.  But  that  which  is  new  and 
essential  in  Christian  ethics  consists  in  just  this,  that  Chris- 
tianity is  the  power  to  transform  moral  obligation  into 
moral  fact. 

c.  This  is  recognised  in  a  third  designation  of  our  science, 
namely,  when  it  is  regarded  as  the  doctrine  of  virtue.  Kant 
also  professed  to  treat  of  ethics  in  his  doctrine  of  virtue  ;  but 
he  did  not  get  beyond  the  demand  for  virtue,  that  is,  he 
substantially  sticks  fast  in  the  law ;  whereas  Christian  ethics 
demands  that  morality  become  a  reality,  as  it  has  been 
manifested  in  Christ  and  is  working  on  in  the  Church.  So 
much,  to  be  sure,  Kant  rightly  emphasized,  that  in  order  to 
morality  there  must  be  an  inward  disposition  as  a  constant 
power,  without  which  right  conduct  would  be  soulless  and 
mechanical.  The  right  moral  disposition,  however,  is  power 
for  virtue.  But  however  certainly  the  notion  of  virtue  must 
be  included  in  the  full  definition  of  our  science,  yet  the 
designation  of  it  as  the  doctrine  of  virtue  would  likewise  not 
embrace  the  whole  realm  of  morality.  Morality  which,  when 
it  takes  a  personal  form,  becomes  complete  in  virtue,  has 
also  essential  reference   to   ethical  good,  or  to  the  objective 


DIFFERENT  NAMES  OF  THE  SCIENCE  OF  MORALITY.  11 

system  of  good  things  in  wliich  the  capacity  for  virtue  finds 
its  appropriate  activity.  But  just  on  that  account  there 
belongs  to  morality  an  objective  rule  as  a  goal,  or  as  a  work 
to  be  done. 

2.  From  a  survey  of  the  three  above-mentioned  chief  ways 
of  conceiving  the  ethical  principle,  it  follows  that  it  presents 
a  threefold  aspect ;  and  we  shall  see  how,  under  the  designa- 
tions, Doctrine  of  the  Good  (Doctrine  of  the  Kingdom  of  God), 
Law  (or  Doctrine  of  Duty),  and  Doctrine  of  Virtue,  are  com- 
prehended three  fundamental  and  connected  forms  of  the 
ethical  principle.  The  most  adequate  designation  of  our 
science  will  doubtless  be  that  in  which  all  three  forms  have 
place.  As  such  designation  there  present  themselves  further- 
more the  terms  Moral  Science  and  Ethics  [the  latter  being  the 
preferable  term]. 

Note. — [In  the  original,  "  Moral,  Ethik,  Sittenlehre,"  the 
words  in  square  brackets  being  added  hy  the  translator,  as 
indicating  the  conclusion  to  which  Dorner  comes  after  an 
etymological  discussion,  much  of  which  would  be  of  no  use 
to  the  merely  English  reader,  inasmuch  as  it  treats  largely 
of  the  etymological  significance  of  German  words.  Moreover, 
the  objections  urged  against  the  use  of  the  word  "  moral," 
however  forcible  they  may  be  to  Germans,  do  not  equally 
bear  against  the  use  of  that  word  in  English.  And  as  tlie 
word  will  be  constantly  used  in  the  translation,  it  seems  best 
to  throw  the  etymological  disquisition  into  the  form  of  a 
note. — Tr.]  The  term  "  Moral,"  discvplina  moralis,  formerly 
much  used,  is  exposed  to  the  objection  that  this  word  looks 
more  to  the  appearance  than  to  the  essence  and  inward  source. 
Mos  as  =  "  usage,"  "  custom,"  may  have  nothing  to  do  with 
the  ethical  life  ;  mores  designates  indeed  the  ethical  character, 
but  as  the  plural  signifies,  not  as  an  inner  unity,  but  as  a 
continuity  of  similar  self-manifestations  of  what  is  within. 
The  terms  Ethik,  Sittenlehre,  on  the  contrary,  present  the 
possibility  of  comprehending  all  three  of  the  fundamental 
forms  of  morality.  Etymologically,  TiQoz  is  the  Ionic  form  of 
'ik;  (which  probably  comes  from  £^w,  to  sit,  as  in  similar 
manner  Sittc  is  connected  with  sitzcn,  Geivohnheit  with 
tvohnen).  ~Hdog,  like  Sitte,  designates  in  the  first  place  what 
is  current,  as  sanctioned  by  usage,  and  so  there  lies  in  it  a 
reference  to  rule  or  law;  and,  secondly,  since  TJdog,  custom 
[^Sitte'],  has  for  its  source  not  merely  individuals  as  such,  but 
objective  communities,  the  word  r&og,  Sittc,  points  to  a  social 


12  §  2.    THE  MEANING  OF  MOEALITY. 

circle  in  which  the  Sitte  governs  or  has  an  existence,  a  home. 
But,  thirdly,  by  riSog  is  meant  not  merely  an  objective  exist- 
ence in  a  social  circle,  as  this  expresses  itself  in  usages  that 
are  possibly  merely  outward  and  mechanical ;  but  it  is 
essential  to  the  word  that  it  denote  the  inward  character, 
whether  of  a  people  or  of  a  person.  Ethos  is  to  the  Greeks 
the  fundamental  mood,  the  disposition  of  the  soul,  or  the 
inner  state  of  character.^  ''H^o;  is  thus  the  seat,  or  the  moral 
vital  element,  in  which  one  has  his  home,  therefore  related 
to  ingenium,  Geist ;  but  even  if  not  exclusively,  yet  chiefly, 
with  an  ethical  meaning,  in  that  rj&og  is  contradistiuguished 
from  rrd&og,  mere  passivity.  So  then  it  designates  the  inward 
ethical  (good  or  evil)  life,  and  comprehends  that  which  has 
become  an  habitual  state,  an  animating  principle,  in  the 
subjective  fundamental  trend  which  is  the  germ  of  virtue  or 
morality.  Similarly  Sittenlehre  points  to  usage  or  law,  and 
to  an  objective  circle  in  which  it  has  validity ;  and  since 
Christian  "  Sittenlehre  "  does  not  suggest  doctrines  of  customs 
(Sitten,  mores),  but  of  Christian  Sitte  as  Sittlichkeit  [morality], 
our  [German]  language  means  by  the  word  also  the  inward 
aspect  of  virtue ;  the  term  Sittlichhcitslehre,  on  the  other 
hand,  would  stamp  ethics  too  one-sidedly  as  the  doctrine  of 
virtue.  Accordingly  Christian  Ethih  or  Sittenlehre  is  the 
science  of  Christian  morality  [ties  christlich  Sittlichen]  in  its 
totality,  the  science  of  that  which  in  Christendom  passes  as 
moral  [das  Sittlichc],  and  which  therefore  constitutes  its 
peculiar  Ethos.^ 

3.  If,  now,  we  have  the  most  adequate  name  for  our  science, 
what,  next,  is  the  more  exact  meaning  of  morality,  concerning 
which  the  science  treats  ?  It  is,  like  the  word  "  spirit,"  hard 
to  define,  because  the  danger  always  is  that  in  the  definition 
the  very  thing  to  be  defined  will  be  presupposed.  The  usual 
method  of  definition  is  to  go  back  to  a  generic  idea,  including 
under  it  various  species,  which  last  are  distinguished  from 
one  another,  and  are  thus  more  exactly  defined.  This  method 
fails  here,  because  there  are  not  several  species  co-ordinate 

'  Cf.  Bonitz,  Worterbuch  zu  Aristotelesf,  article  ?i6oi. 

-  [It  may  here  be  remarked  further,  that  Dorner  uses  very  frequently  the 
phrases  ''das  Sittlkhe"  and  "das  Ethische"  to  denote  morality  in  general, 
as  a  fact  and  as  an  object  of  thought.  The  literal  rendering,  "  the  moral,"  or 
"the  ethical,"  would  be  un-English  and  harsh.  They  are  accordingly  com- 
monly translated  "morality,"  as,  e.g.,  just  above,  "the  science  of  Christian 
morality"  (German  :  "die  Wissenschaft  deschristUch  SiltUchen"),  but  occasion- 
ally, "the  ethical  (moral)  element  (principle,  sphere,  etc.)." — Te.] 


MORALITY  IN  ITS  FORMAL  ASPECT.  13 

with  morality.  Morality  is  itself  the  highest  thing,  the  one 
thing  of  its  kind — ens  sui  generis.  But  yet,  on  the  other 
hand,  it  is  a  mode  of  spiritual  existence,  beside  which 
there  are  other  things  of  spiritual  worth  which  must  be 
definitely  distinguished  from  it.  Let  us  seek,  then,  by 
distinguishing  it  from  other  things,  in  relation  to  both  its 
form  and  its  contents,  to  come  more  nearly  to  the  nature  of 
morality. 

a.  As  to  its  formal  aspect,  we  must  indeed,  with  Eothe, 
attach  importance  to  the  consideration  that  in  ethics  the 
function  of  personality  or  of  self-determination  is  essential. 
But  if  from  this  the  definition  should  be  derived :  That  is 
moral  which  comes  to  pass  through  the  self-determination  of 
the  person,  this  would,  it  is  true,  express  a  characteristic  of 
that  which  is  moral,  as  distinguished  from  that  which  is 
merely  physical ;  but  the  definition  would  be  unsatisfactory 
in  a  twofold  respect.  The  playing  of  a  child  upon  whom  the 
consciousness  of  an  ethical  rule  has  not  yet  dawned,  is  not  yet 
to  be  placed  under  the  category  of  the  ethical,  although  will, 
self-determination,  and  consciousness  need  not  be  wanting  in 
it ;  it  belongs  to  the  realm  of  the  ante-ethical. 

Again,  tlie  personal  self-determination  may  be  an  abnormal, 
immoral  one;  and  in  this  aspect  the  definition  which  stops  short 
with  formal  personal  self-determination  would  be  satisfactory 
only  if  moral  science  were  the  science  just  as  much  of  immorality 
as  of  morality.  Xow  we  have  indeed  already  acknowledged  that 
the  word  moral  can  be  taken  in  an  ambiguous  sense,  and  that  the 
immoral  no  less  than  the  moral  necessarily  presupposes  personal 
self-determination.  Still,  strictly  speaking,  the  one  cannot  be  of 
as  much  importance  as  the  other  to  ethics,  for  ethics  is  concerned 
first  and  above  all  with  the  ethically  normal  or  good.  I'rom 
this  the  notion  of  evil  comes  of  itself,  as  the  absolute  contrary 
of  moral  good ;  the  notion  of  moral  good  is  not  derived  from 
that  of  evil,  but  vice  versa  the  former  only  is  an  original 
notion  which  can  be  grasped  without  the  notion  of  evil 
having  been  previously  given.  True,  Lactantius  says,  malum 
intcrprctamentum  loni ;  and  it  is  beyond  dispute  that  this 
distinguishing  of  the  notion  of  the  good  as  the  contrary  of  evil 
invests  the  former  with  a  new  and  greater  definiteness;  but 
the  notion  of  evil  is  so  far  forth  absolutely  dependent  on  that 


14:  §  2.    THE  MEANING  OF  MOEALITY. 

of  Qood,  that  I  must  have  beforehand  a  notion  of  what  crood 
is  in  order  to  know  what  evil  is.  We  shall  not  be  able, 
therefore,  in  the  deiinition  of  ethics  to  treat  both  sorts  of 
personal  self-determination  as  equally  essential. 

On  the  other  hand,  in  ethics  itself  evil  cannot  be  disregarded, 
as  Schleiermacher  in  his  Fliilosophische  Ethih  was  inclined  to  do  ; 
but  in  ethical  discussions  the  notion  of  evil  will  have  to  take  only 
a  secondary  position  dependent  on  that  of  good.  Empirically, 
indeed,  evil  exists  together  with  good,  at  least  now.  But  as 
it  did  not  always  have  to  be  thus,  so  it  will  not  always  be 
thus.  When  now  it  is  considered  that  personal  self-determi- 
nation, ill  order  to  be  called  morally  good,  must  conform  to  a 
rule  by  which  caprice  and  hesitation  between  various  possi- 
bilities are  excluded,  then  it  is  seen  that  the  morally  good, 
whatever  it  may  consist  in,  has  somewhat  in  itself  which  is 
wanting  in  everythmg  else,  namely,  the  power  absolutely  to 
put  under  obligation  and  allegiance  to  itself.  Kant  stopped 
short  at  this  formal  feature  of  the  absolute  obligatoriness  of 
the  morally  good,  without  expressing  himself  more  definitely 
as  to  its  nature.  He  assumes  that  moral  good  is  sufficiently 
distinguished  from  everything  else  by  the  form  which  belongs 
to  it,  and  to  it  alone,  of  absolute  obligatoriness ;  and  that  what 
is  moral  is  to  be  distinguished  from  what  is  immoral  by  the 
fact  that  the  latter  is  destitute  of  that  absolute  originality. 
Subjectively  expressed,  this  means :  The  will  is  good,  when  it 
acknowledges  that  absolute  obligatoriness  ;  the  good  disposition 
consists  in  respectful  submission  to  the  Categorical  Imperative. 
But  it  will  not  suffice  to  stop  with  this  merely  formal  feature, 
and  to  find  the  good  disposition  insured  by  the  simple  fact 
that  there  is  respect  for  the  absolute  obligatoriness  of  law  in 
the  abstract.  For  if  nothing  is  said  about  the  contents  of  the 
law,  or  about  what  that  is  which  is  absolutely  binding,  then 
in  order  to  a  good  disposition  it  would  only  be  needed  that 
the  law  should  be  willed — should  be  conceived  as  absolutely 
obligatory — although  in  itself  it  might  be  even  not  obli- 
gatory, nay,  might  itself  even  be  evil.  It  would  be  the 
good  intention  alone  through  which  anything  would  receive 
the  stamp  of  good ;  there  would  be  room  even  for  the 
Jesuitical  principle.  So,  then,  only  that  disposition  is 
entitled  to  be    called   "ood    which   is   directed   towards   the 


THE  SUBSTANCE  OF  MORALITY.  15 

right  thing.     Wisdom  belongs  essentially  to  the  morally  good 
disposition. 

Note. — Kant,  in  his  definition  of  the  meaning  of  morality, 
does  not  find  the  bridge  which  leads  over  from  the  merely 
formal,  to  the  substantial,  notion,  and  by  means  of  which  alone 
the  definition  is  precisely  enough  fixed. 

l.  The  substantial  element,  by  means  of  which  ethical  good 
is  constituted  such,  might  be  found  stated  in  this  proposition 
of  Schleiermacher's  Philosophische  Ethik :  The  ethical  is  the 
union  of  reason  and  nature, — a  proposition  with  which  Eothe 
substantially  agrees.^  Since  reason  and  mind  are  abstractions, 
having  no  morals  (only  persons  have  morals),  Eothe  expresses 
Schleiermacher's  thought  thus :  "  Morality  is  the  appropriation 
of  the  material  (earthly)  nature  by  the  human  personality  as 
accomplished  by  the  determining  influence  of  personality  upon 
nature."  This  leaves  Christianity  out  of  consideration,  and 
stops  with  morality  in  general.  But  the  appropriation  of 
nature,  as  also  the  union  between  reason  and  nature,  can  take 
place  in  a  twofold  manner :  either  so  that  nature,  the  material 
world,  is  subjected  to  mind,  or,  vice  versa,  mind  to  nature.  There 
is,  too,  a  false  union  of  mind  and  nature.  It  may,  indeed,  be 
said  that  reason  as  such  is  security  for  the  good,  and  likewise 
that  personality,  in  distinction  Irom  individuality,  is  that 
which  has  taken  up  into  itself  what  is  of  universal  validity, 
so  that  an  abnormal  union  of  nature  and  reason  (or  person- 
ality) seems  to  be  excluded  by  the  very  notion  of  the  latter. 
But  by  common  usage  we  speak  of  errors  of  the  reason,  and 
of  an  evil  tendency  of  the  personality,  so  that  by  neither  of 
these  is  expressed  what  that  is  which  is  good,  but  rather  this 
still  remains  merely  presupposed.  When  Eothe  says,  further, 
that  that  personal  self-determination  is  ethically  good  which  is 
consonant  with  the  notion  of  personality,""^  it  must  be  remarked 
that  the  very  thing  in  question  is,  what  is  consonant  with 
personality  ?  And  if  it  should  be  said,  it  is  that  which 
conforms  to  what  is  normal  in  personality,  then,  since  nature 
too  has  its  law  and  its  norm,  we  need  first  to  be  told  what  is 
the  characteristic  feature  of  the  ethical  norm.  Furthermore, 
the  union  of  reason  with  nature,  even  if  this  union  were  to 
mean  supremacy  of  mind  over  nature,  does  not  as  yet  embrace 
i  Theol.  EtJdk,  2nd  ed.  §  102  ;  2ud  ed.  p.  427  ;  cf.  §  87.         ^  lUd.  p.  431. 


16  §  2.    THE  MEANING  OF  MORALITY. 

all  that  is  morally  good.  On  the  contrary,  the  primary 
thing  is  the  inward  union,  the  harmonizing  of  the  powers 
of  the  soul,  that  is,  the  normal  self-shaping  of  the  person, 
the  right  shaping  of  the  soul,  as  being  the  power  to 
mould  nature  without  us,  as  well  as  our  own  body,  in  the 
right  way. 

We  come  a  step  farther,  perhaps,  by  bringing  in  the  notions 
of  purpose  and  of  worth.  It  belongs  essentially  to  the  will,  as 
already  observed,  to  direct  itself  towards  an  object.  That 
towards  which  it  directs  itself  has  for  it  a  worth,  or  is  held 
by  it  to  be  a  good  thing.  Now,  while  it  can  set  before  itself, 
as  its  object,  things  of  endless  variety,  it  will  always  ascribe 
a  worth  to  that  with  which  it  is  engrossed ;  but  these  values 
may  be  only  of  a  finite,  nay,  merely  specious  sort.  Now  that 
which  has  merely  this  character  is  not  yet  the  ethically  good. 
Life,  harmony,  beauty,  and  intelligence,  or  knowledge,  have 
doubtless  a  value ;  of  none  of  these  in  itself,  however,  can  it 
be  said  that  it  is  intrinsically  of  absolute  value;  for  this 
highest  predicate  belongs  only  to  the  ethically  good,  and 
distinguishes  it  from  all  other  forms  of  good,  and  exalts  it 
above  them.  Ethical  good  is  not  yet  conceived  of,  unless  it 
is  conceived  of  as  the  absolutely  valuable  over  against  all 
other  existing  things ;  but  when  it  is  conceived  of,  it  is  con- 
ceived of  in  its  unique  sacred  majesty.  But  casting,  by  way 
of  anticipation,  a  glance  from  this  point  at  the  distinctive 
peculiarity  of  Christian  ethics,  we  may  say  that,  to  the 
Christian,  what  is  morally  good  consists  in  this :  that  the  first 
creation,  the  material  and  the  psychical,  accordingly  also  the 
natural  person,  is  appropriated  by  the  second  creation,  or  by 
the  Christian  pncuma,  through  the  agency  of  the  self-determi- 
nation of  the  ego.  Speaking  comprehensively,  and  distinguishing 
from  all  others  Christian  morality  as  the  perfect  morality,  we 
may  therefore  say :  Christian  ethics  is  the  science  of  that 
which  is  absolutely  worthy, — of  that  which,  as  to  form,  is 
worked  out  through  continual  personal  self-determination ; 
but,  as  to  substance,  is  to  be  described  as  the  appropriation, 
by  means  of  the  divine  jjnezwjia,  of  the  natural  personality, 
and,  with  it,  of  the  first  creation. 

ISfotc  1. — The  bringing  in  of  the  notion  of  worth  might  seem 
to  lead  to  a  utilitarian  conception  of  morality.     But  that  would 


§  3.  EELATION  OF  CHKISTIAN  TO  PHILOSOPHICAL  ETHICS.       1 7 

be  the  case  only  if  the  worth  in  question  were  a  worth  merely 
because  it  furnishes  enjoyment  or  satisfaction  to  the  person ; 
but  a  thing  having  this  kind  of  value  would  have  its  value,  not 
in  itself,  but  simply  in  its  relation  to  other  things,  as  being 
useful.  But  then  ethical  good  would  be  only  of  limited  and 
not  of  absolute  value. 

Note  2. — It  might  be  objected  to  what  has  been  said  above, 
that  to  knowledge  or  cognition  also  an  absolute  worth  must  not 
be  denied.  But  that  cannot  hold  of  every  sort  of  cognition. 
Even  thinking  about  God  and  His  attributes,  if  it  is  exer- 
cised only  as  about  an  object  of  mathematics,  is  not  of  absolute 
worth,  even  if  it  does  not,  as  is  probable,  lead  to  false  proposi- 
tions. On  the  other  liand,  sucli  a  cognition  as,  joined  with 
love,  vitally  knows  God  as  the  highest  and  original  Good,  and 
thus  thinking  enters  in  thought  into  a  responsive  relation  to 
God,  is  indeed  of  absolute  worth  in  itself,  and  is  something  to 
be  aimed  at  on  its  own  account.  Such  knowledge,  however,  is 
wisdom,  a  virtue  belonging  therefore  to  morality  itself;  and  it 
partakes  of  the  character  of  self-determination,  of  personality. 
And  the  case  is  similar  with  religion.  We  should  not,  to  be 
sure,  make  morality  and  religion  identical,  but  religion  also  in 
itself  has  absolute  value,  and  is  an  ultimate  end.  But  so  far 
forth  as  it  is  this,  it  too  is  a  virtue,  piety,  and  is  included  in  the, 
notion  of  the  ethical. 


§  3.  Relation  of  Theological  or  Christian  Ethics  to 
Fldlosoijhical  Ethics. 

The  relation  between  Christian  and  philosophical  ethics  is- 
neither  that  of  necessary  opposition  or  contradiction, 
nor  that  of  identity,  but  that  of  difference,  which  is 
destined  to  become  continually  less  and  less.  This 
adjustment  advances  in  proportion  as  Christian  ethics 
appropriates  to  itself  everything  belonging  to  the  first 
creation,  and  as  philosophical  ethics  recognises  the 
reasonableness  or  truth  of  Christianity,  and  so  becomes 
Christian.  Yet  this  adjustment  is  accomplished  by 
continuing  to  treat  the  two  separately  ;  thus  separated 
they  tend  towards  union  in  the  process  of  conflict. 
The  dissimilarity  of  the  two,  so  long  as  it  lasts  (as  also 
the  likeness),  is  partly  one  of  form,  partly  one  of  sub 

B 


13      §  3.  RELATION  OF  CHRISTIAN  TO  PHILOSOPHICAL  ETHICS. 

stance.      But  it  points  back  to  the  difference  between 
natural  and  Christian  ethics. 

1.  Tlie  relation  between  philosophical  and  theological  ethics 
is  the  same  as  that  between  philosophy  and  Christian  theology 
in  general,  and  points  back  to  the  deeper  and  more  general 
distinction  between  the  first  and  the  second  creation.  In  the 
first  place,  it  is  to  be  insisted  that  their  relation  to  each  other 
is  not  that  of  an  original  inherent  contradiction.  True,  the 
doubt  has  often  arisen  in  the  Church,  whether  there  can  be  a 
moral  philosophy,  a  natural  moral  knowledge  not  first  emanat- 
ing from  historic  revelation,  be  the  obstacle  to  it  the  imperfect 
intellectual  equipment  of  man,  or  the  disturbance  occasioned 
by  sin.  The  first  view  appears  in  Socinianism,  which,  the  less 
its  doctrine  of  revelation  contributes  to  dogmatics,  so  much 
the  more  traces  our  moral  knowledge  back  to  revelation.  The 
other  view  is  more  often  heard  expressed  in  the  Church.  Not 
so  much,  indeed,  in  the  Eoman  Catholic  Church,  which,  how- 
ever, is  inclined  to  depreciate  natural  knowledge  in  favour 
of  the  authority  of  the  only  infallible  Church  ;  to  which  must 
be  added  that  its  notion  of  Christian  morality  comes  into 
collision  with  natural  morality.  But  neither  the  authority 
of  the  Church,  nor  the  doctrine  of  a  twofold  morality,  could 
be  made  to  work  in  the  Evangelical  Church.  On  the  otlier 
hand,  here  it  was  the  doctrine  of  natural  sinfulness  and 
obscuration  of  reason,  which,  when  carried  to  the  extreme, 
led  to  a  similar  result,  viz.  to  the  doctrine  that  a  true  ethical 
knowledge  is  to  be  denied  to  the  natural  man. 

But  by  going  too  far  in  this  respect  the  danger  is  incurred  of 
excusing  sin  and  of  making  difficult  the  transition  to  sorrow 
and  repentance ;  for  the  degree  of  guilt  depends  upon  the 
measure  of  moral  knowledge  to  which  the  evil  is  opposed 
(Luke  xii.  47,  48).  Were  there  in  the  natural  man  no 
knowledge  of  duty  at  all,  as  there  is  not  in  the  brute, 
then  a  moral  perception  could  not  be  implanted  in  him 
supplementarily  from  witliout,  either  through  the  authority  of 
the  Church  or  through  revelation.  He  could  be  instructed 
about  moral  requirements ;  but  that  this  instruction  is  abso- 
lutely binding  upon  him,  or  is  duty,  he  cannot  know,  unless 
he  at  least  possesses  the  natural  knowledge  that  he  is  under 


ALLEGED  CONTKADICTION  BETWEEN  THEM.  19 

obligation  to  do  that  which  is  good, — or  that  which  proceeds 
from  God,  the  supreme  source  of  all  moral  law, — and  to  avoid 
the  opposite.  But  the  gravest  objection  is  this,  viz.  that  if 
all  natural  moral  knowledge  should  be  denied,  the  transi- 
tion to  Christian  faith  could  be  made  only  by  an  act  of 
moral  caprice.  To  reject  redemption  would  be  excusable, 
yes,  natural,  if  there  were  no  such  knov/ledge  of  good  and 
evil  as  enables  one  to  perceive  the  necessity  of  redemption 
and  the  duty  of  seeking  help  from  it.  But  since,  according  to 
Eom.  ii.  13  sqq.,  John  i.  5,  v.  38,  even  in  fallen  man  the  light 
of  conscience  is  still  to  be  recognised,  and  since,  on  the  other 
hand,  it  is  obvious  enough  that  to  know"  good  and  to  do  it  are 
two  very  different  things,  and  that  even  by  means  of  higher 
moral  knowledge  the  need  of  redemption  is  as  yet  not  removed, 
but  only  the  consciousness  of  this  need  augmented,  therefore 
the  objections  against  the  possibility  of  a  philosophical  ethics 
more  and  more  subsided  in  the  Church.  And,  indeed,  it 
would  have  been  an  unjustifiable  loss  to  ethical  knowledge, 
if  all  the  ethical  labours,  thoughts,  and  works  of  the  ancients, 
of  a  Plato,  an  Aristotle,  the  Stoics,  Cicero,  Seneca,  Marcus 
Aurelius,  were  to  be  counted  for  nothing.  Even  Melanchthon, 
therefore,  wrote  a  Philosopliia  Moralis. 

2,  Since  philosophy  has  raised  itself  to  an  independent 
position,  it  has  not  seldom  affirmed,  that  between  philosophical 
and  Christian  ethics  there  is  an  irreconcilable  contradiction, 
and  that  there  remains  for  Christian  ethics  no  special  place. 
We  need  not  here  consider  those  who,  like  the  materialists, 
defend  an  ethics  of  selfishness ;  there  are  others,  too,  who 
say  that  a  historical  element  is  essential  to  Christian  ethics, 
but  that  that  condemns  this  ethics  in  advance  to  an  un- 
scientific form.  Christianity,  they  affirm,  impairs  moral 
autonomy  and  freedom,  because  it  sets  up  the  moral  com- 
mands as  commands  of  God,  and  thus  obedience  to  them 
becomes  service,  and  the  motive  for  moral  conduct  is  vitiated 
through  the  fear  of  God,  or  through  regard  to  future  reward. 
Finally,  it  is  said,  human  freedom  is  violated  by  the  doctrine 
of  grace. 

But  these  objections,  all  of  which  are  rooted  in  a  false  con- 
ception of  Christianity,  would  hold  equally  against  all  connec- 
tion between  ethics  and  religion,  and  consequently  would  lead 


20      §  3.  EELATIOX  OF  CHRISTIAN  TO  PHILOSOPHICAL  ETHICS. 

to  the  exclusion  of  the  virtue  of  piety  from  ethics,  and  therefore 
to  the  mutilation  of  this  science.  The  above-mentioned  objec- 
tions are  especially  familiar  in  the  Kantian  philosophy,  which, 
however,  on  its  own  part  does  not  avoid  a  self-contradiction  ;  for 
if  the  contradiction  between  the  moral  ideal  and  reality  is  an 
eternal  and  insuperable  one,  it  leads  legitimately  to  doubt  con- 
cerning the  right,  and  the  absolute  obligatoriness  of  such  a  power- 
less, impotent  ideal.  Therefore  in  the  following  period,  which 
threw  itself  into  the  arms  of  Empiricism  and  of  natural  science, 
appeared  Anthropologism,  This  doctrine,  because  it  does  not 
recognise  the  existence  of  an  ethical  Absolute  as  the  primeval 
power  over  all,  but  gives  up  the  idea  of  God,  retains  only  that 
of  conditioned  limited  being,  casts  aside  all  absolute  binding 
legislation,  and  therefore  does  not  get  beyond  mere  caprice 
and  utilitarianism ;  but  thereby  it  impairs  the  very  essence  of 
human  nature.  For  the  strength  and  security  of  the  rational 
essence  of  our  nature  lies  in  God. 

3.  Both  these  assumptions  of  an  essential  contradiction 
between  Christian  ethics  and  natural  or  philosophical  ethics, 
Christianity  refuses  to  admit ;  on  the  contrary,  it  recognises  a 
certain  relationship  between  the  latter  and  itself  which  lies  in 
the  very  saying,  "  The  law  is  our  tutor  to  bring  us  unto 
Christ."  The  first  creation,  although  deformed  by  sin,  is  yet 
the  object  of  divine  preservation  ;  it  is  implied  in  the  second 
creation  and  constitutes  its  basis  ;  it  is  perverted,  but  not  as  to 
substance :  the  substance  of  the  world  has  remained  meta- 
physically good.  This  afiiuity  between  Christian  and  philo- 
sophical ethics  appears  in  respect  both  to  matter  and  to  form. 
Christian  morality,  like  natural  morality,  requires  a  material 
something  on  which  to  act ;  even  for  Christian  morality  there 
is  no  other,  no  purely  spiritual,  world,  but  merely  one  and  the 
same  world,  that  of  the  first  creation.  The  duties  of  the  soul 
towards  itself  and  towards  the  body  are  binding  in  Christian 
ethics  also.  Marriage,  the  family,  civil  and  political  com- 
munities, had  place  before  Christianity  itself;  an  inner  logic 
inheres  in  their  very  essence,  and  approves  what  promotes 
them  and  rejects  the  opposite  ;  and  if  a  moral  sense  is  united 
with  the  perception  of  the  inner  nature  of  all  these  institutions, 
then  we  have  a  moral  law  enriching  itself  more  and  more, — a 
law  which  Christianity,  too,  cannot   but   recognise.     Besides 


THE  DISTINCTION  BETWEEN  THEM.  21 

this  material  likeness  there  is  a  formal  one  also.  Natural 
morals,  like  Christian  morals,  must  operate  on  the  rational 
faculties  of  thought  and  will.  Personal  self-determination,  as 
both  must  acknowledge,  is  indispensable  if  anything  is  to  come 
into  the  department  of  morality,  even  though  morality  be  taken 
only  in  the  wider  sense. 

4.  jSTevertlieless  it  must  be  maintained  that  there  is  as 
little  a  direct  identity,  as  an  essential  contradiction,  between 
natural  or  philosophical  ethics  and  Christian  ethics.  The 
discussions  on  ethics  from  the  theological  and  the  philosophical 
sides  exhibit  in  fact  great  differences  still  existing.  Theo- 
logical ethics  is  wont  to  regard  as  its  basis  the  inner  ethics, 
which  occupies  itself  with  the  individual.-^  It  considers  the 
inward  healing,  purifying,  strengthening  of  the  individual, 
especially  in  the  religious  sphere  ;  and  so  accordingly  ascetics, 
which  usually  forms  no  part  of  philosophical  ethics,  occupies 
an  important  place  in  it.  Philosophical  ethics  directs  itself 
rather  to  the  worldly  side  of  morality,  to  what  is  wrought,  to 
social  relations,  possibly  also  to  the  consideration  of  moral 
conduct  towards  one's  self.  So  far  as  the  individual  is  taken 
into  view,  philosophical  ethics  pays  little  attention  to  the 
religious  element  in  the  moral  nature  of  man,  and  in  general 
to  the  moral  inclination  towards  God  ;  all  the  more,  on  the 
contrary,  it  lays  stress  on  the  natural  moral  power,  on  self- 
imposed  laws,  and  on  the  fulfilling  of  the  law.  Natural 
reason  is  here  commonly  made  the  suurcc  of  ethical  knowledge, 
being  assumed  to  be  everywhere  essentially  the  same.  Natural 
reason  does  not  exact  of  its  pupils  that  they  first  pass 
through  a  moral  and  religious  process,  but  taking  for  granted 
that  men  understand  and  assent,  it  addresses  itself  without 
any  further  concern  to  the  general  rational  constitution. 
Logically  connected  with  this  is  the  fact  that  philosophy  is 
wont  to  take  less  account  of  wickedness,  and  therefore  also  of 
the  atonement.  It  can  therefore  be  said,  in  this  respect,  that 
theological  ethics  sharjDcns  the  moral  conscience  of  philo- 
sophical ethics,  taking  the  place  of  ascetics  in  relation  to  it; 
as,  on  the  other  hand,  it  can  be  said  that  philosophical  ethics 
sharpens  the  logical  conscience  of  theological  ethics.  They 
support  each  other  by  their  close  connection. 

1  Cf.  Frank,  System  dcr  Christl.  SittUchkeit,  i.  §  5,  p.  49  sq. 


22       §3.  EELATION  OF  CHPJSTIAN  TO  PHILOSOPHICAL  ETHICS. 

But  the  nature  of  the  case  also  forbids  the  direct  identifica- 
tion of  theological  and  philosophical  ethics,  although  this  has 
been  attempted  on  both  sides.  On  the  philosophical  side,  it 
has  been  said  that  the  ethical  subject-matter  is  the  same, 
since  there  is  only  one  kind  of  morality  ;  look  away  from 
the  breadth  and  fulness  of  the  historical  additions  in  theo- 
logical morals,  strip  away  this  positive  element  which  belongs 
merely  to  the  form  of  presenting  Christianity,  and  then,  it 
is  said,  we  see  that  the  remaining  ethical  kernel  of  theo- 
logical ethics  is  the  same  as  is  peculiar  also  to  philosophical, 
only  that  the  latter  adheres  to  a  stricter  scientific  form.  But 
as  for  the  strictness  of  the  demands  of  science,  theological 
ethics,  if  duly  regardful  of  itself,  will  not  consent  to  be  left 
behind  the  philosophical,  as  Eothe's  Tlieolorjisdw  Ethik,  2nd 
edition,  evinces  with  especial  force.  And  then  as  to  the 
historical  element  in  Christianity,  this  is  not  merely  an  idle 
scholarly  addition  to  it,  or  a  form  of  presenting  it,  and  has  not 
merely  the  importance  of  external  authority.  It  is  itself  of 
ideal  and  real  ethical  significance,  and  is  an  essential  factor  in 
making  morality  actual  in  humanity  ;  above  all  is  this  true  of 
the  person  of  the  ethical  Mediator.  An  ethics  which  should 
conclude  its  system  without  Christ  would  fail  to  preserve  the 
very  kernel  of  that  which  in  Christianity  lays  claim  to  be  ethics. 

Nevertheless  not  philosophers  merely,  but  theologians  also, 
have  assumed  an  essential  identity  between  Christian  and 
philosophical  or  even  natural  morals.  In  the  last  century 
it  was  a  favourite  mode  of  speech,  that  there  is  properly 
no  strife  except  about  dogmatic  points  ;  that  in  the  ethical 
sphere  Illuminism  and  Christian  theology  are  essentially  at 
one  ;  that  both  advocate  the  highest  interests  of  humanity. 
It  must  be  acknowledged  that  the  ethical  element  in  Chris- 
tianity is  in  certain  respects  more  easily  grasped  than  the 
dogmatical,  that  it  commends  itself  more  readily  to  the  uni- 
versal reason,  which  is  pleased  with  v/hat  is  praiseAvorthy  and 
of  good  report,  and  what  tlie  natural  man  inwardly  approves. 
Finally,  too,  Christian  faith  is  conscious  that  it  represents  the 
true  universal  reason.  Nevertheless  it  cannot  be  granted  that 
natural  and  Christian  ethics  are  identical.  The  most  import- 
ant difference  is  that  the  former  never  gets  essentially  beyond 
the  Ought,  the  moral  requirement.     Christianity  affirms  that 


THE  TWO  NOT  IDENTICAL.  23 

it  carries  in  itself  the  real,  operative  principle  of  virtue  ; 
and  it  has  evinced  this  in  a  history  of  many  centuries,  in 
which  it  has  in  part  worked  out,  in  part  begun,  a  regeneration 
of  mankind.  Christian  ethics  has  its  life  in  the  Divine  Spirit, 
the  source  of  the  second,  the  perfect  creation ;  likewise  also 
Christianity  discloses  to  faith  a  pure  higher  world  of  fellow- 
ship, the  kingdom  of  God,  in  which  heavenly  forces  have 
incorporated  themselves  into  the  world  of  created  beings. 
This  has  the  more  significance,  inasmuch  as  Christian  ethics 
makes  the  kingdom  of  God  proceed  from  the  continual 
overcoming  of  sin,  of  guilt,  and  of  error,  and  makes  earnest 
work  of  the  conflict  with  them  ;  whereas  philosophy  likes  to 
look  away  from  this  night-side  of  human  life,  but  is  therefore 
accustomed  to  move  in  an  abstract  and  unreal  realm. 

This  relation  to  sin,  which  is  essential  to  Christian  ethics, 
involves,  as  a  consequence,  that  Eedemption,  the  historical 
person  of  the  ethical  Mediator,  is  an  integral  factor  of  Chris- 
tian ethics  ;  nothing  but  love  to  God  transformed  into  love  to 
Christ  is  true  Christian  love.  This  historical  element  is 
indeed  a  new  element,  whose  place  cannot  be  supplied  by 
lb  priori  thinking,  but  is  yet  not  on  that  account  a  merely 
accidental  thing,  outward  and  empirical,  and  unattainable  by 
the  rational  being.  For  reason,  rather,  Christianity  exists  ; 
to  reason  it  directs  itself.  The  inward  experience  which 
faith  brings  is  clothed  with  the  consciousness  of  inward  truth. 
The  new  historical  element,  as  it  is  not  contrary  to  reason, 
must  also  not  be  beyond  reason  ;  to  faith  it  is  the  eternal  and 
abiding  revelation  of  eternal  truth  and  reality.  But,  it  is  true, 
this  union  of  the  natural  man  with  Christianity  is  possible 
only  by  means  of  a  religious  attitude  of  mind.  The  self- 
surrender  that  faith  makes  leads  to  an  assimilation  of  Chris- 
tianity on  the  part  of  the  reason,  which  is  made  for  Chris- 
tianity. By  faith  reason  is  not  suspended,  but  freed  from 
error  and  sin,  and  led  on  towards  perfection.  The  same 
Paul  who  says  that  the  gospel  is  to  the  Jews  a  stumbling- 
block,  and  to  the  Greeks  seeking  after  wisdom  a  foolishness, 
adds  that  it  is  nevertheless  in  itself  a  foolishness  of  God 
which  is  wiser  than  men,  yea,  the  power  of  God  and  the 
wisdom  of  God.^ 

1  Cf.  my  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  Pisteology,  i.  pp.  33-168. 


24      §  3.  RELATION  OF  CHRISTIAN  TO  PHILOSOrillCAL  ETHICS. 

5.  And  now,  summing  wp  the  foregoing,  we  can  define  exactly 
the  relation  of  Christian  ethics  both  to  natural  and  to  philo- 
sophical ethics.  As  to  the  relation  between  the  first  two, 
identity  can  at  all  events  not  be  affirmed;  that  would  imply 
that  the  second  creation  is  to  be  derived  from  the  first ;  but 
this  is  not  admissible,  even  if  we  might  leave  out  of  account 
the  power  of  sin  which  has  entered  into  the  first  creation. 
But  all  true  moral  perception  is-  not  thereby  denied  to  the 
natural  man ;  and  when  now  Christianity  is  received  in  the 
act  of  faith,  the  natural  and  the  acquired  Christian  hnovdedge 
of  morality  may  very  well,  to  the  mind  of  Christian  moralists, 
floio  together  into  one.  For  the  human  reason  just  as  truly 
■  obtains  an  inward  certainty  concerning  Christianity  as  it 
possesses  such  a  certainty  concerning  the  natural  moral 
cognitions;  for  without  Christianity  the  general  moral  cog- 
nitions of  men  would  become  uncertain,  since  a  moral  ideal 
set  up  without  the  possibility  of  its  being  realized  would  for 
ever  be  a  specious  illusion.  But  because  it  is  not  necessary 
that  the  natural  and  the  ethical,  however  different,  should 
remain  for  ever  separate,  or  even  contrary  to  each  other, 
therefore  it  follows,  secondly,  concerning  the  relation  of 
Christian  ethics  to  philosophical  ethics,  that  they  need  not 
be  opposed.  As  there  is  no  necessity  that  theological  ethics 
be  unscientific  or  blind  towards  the  first  creation,  so  there  is 
also  no  necessity  that  philosopliy  he  and  remain  irreligious  or 
even  non-Christian.  It  is  the  aim  of  Christianity  to  bring  the 
first  and  the  second  creation  to  a  mutual  recognition  and  under- 
standing. By  this  it  is  meant  that  theological  ethics  must 
also  endeavour  to  become  veritably  a  science,  and  that  philo- 
sophical ethics  can  attain  to  its  perfection  only  by  becoming 
Christian,  and  thereby  embracing  the  whole  realm  of  morals. 

When  certain  modern  thinkers  reject  natural  theology, 
either  on  the  ground  that  Christian  doctrine  is  vitiated  by 
it,  or  on  the  ground  that  there  is  no  natural  theology,  they 
must  logically  reject  also  all  natural  ethics  for  one  or 
the  other  of  the  above-named  reasons.  But  to  deny  to  the 
natural  man  all  moral  cognition,  is  opposed  alike  to  experience 
and  to  the  doctrine  of  the  Bible.  This  would  also  leave  no 
point  of  connection  for  a  knowledge  which  is  to  be  communi- 
cated from  without ;  especially  would  a  revelation  be  unable 


THEIR  MUTUAL  DEPENDENCE.  25 

to  attain  its  object;  and  on  that  account  this  opinion  is  seldom 
heard.  A  more  frequent  notion,  on  the  other  hand,  is  that 
natural  ethics  and  Christian  ethics  are  two  irreconcilable 
things.  But  Christianity  claims  the  right  to  regard  all  ethical 
truth,  wherever  it  may  be  found,  as  belonging  to  itself.  The 
same  Logos  that  appeared  in  Christ  is  also  the  prime  agent  in 
the  first  creation,  and  cannot  therefore  be  in  contradiction  with 
Christianity.  To  be  sure,  abnormalness  has  entered  into  the 
first  creation,  and  thereby  a  contradiction  of  Christian  morality  ; 
but  even  in  the  man  inured  to  what  is  abnormal,  there  still 
inlieres  a  secret  ethical  knowledge,  that  is,  one  capable  of  being 
awakened,  which  condemns  this  abnormalness,  and  which  can 
itself  be  enucleated.  Besides  this,  Christian  ethics,  since  it 
also  embodies  in  itself  natural  ethical  knowledge,  can  purify 
the  latter  from  its  morbid  adulterations,  while  yet  this  influence 
need  not  be  felt  by  the  natural  reason  to  be  a  foreign  ordinance. 
If,  now,  the  first  creation  belongs  to  Christian  ethics  as  well  as 
to  general  philosophical  ethics,  without  there  being,  tlierefore, 
any  necessity  that  these  two  be  brought  into  contradiction 
with  each  other,  then  it  must  be  possible  for  one  and  the 
same  person  to  produce  (as,  e.g.,  Schleiermacher  has  done)  a 
Christian  and  a  philosophical  ethics,  the  latter  being  confined 
to  the  natural  moral  knowdedge  derived  from  tlie  reason. 

Now  it  may  indeed  be  said  that  reason,  which  is  often  appealed 
to  as  to  sometliing  fixed  and  universally  the  same,  is,  on  the  con- 
trary, something  very  variable,  subject  to  history  and  to  growth, 
and  that  to  this  history  belongs  essentially  also  the  influence  of 
Christianity;  so  that  the  difference  between  Christian  ethics  and 
the  ethics  of  natural  reason  threatens  to  become  a  fluctuating 
one.  But  Christian  morality  is  wrought  out  through  a  process 
of  redemption  from  sin  and  guilt ;  and  this  forms  a  distinction 
between  it  and  the  ethics  of  natural  reason,  which  is  essential, 
and  not  to  be  obliterated.  But  by  this  it  is  not  denied  that 
it  is  still  the  duty  of  philosopliical  ethics  to  become  Christian ; 
as,  on  the  other  hand.  Christian  ethics  has  to  demand  of  itself 
that  it  be  strictly  scientific,  and  so  at  the  same  time  the 
expression  of  the  philosophic  spirit.  Philosophical  ethics  can 
become  Christian,  for  the  philosopher  can  recognise  it  as 
reasonable  that  he  subject  himself  to  the  ethico  -  religious 
process  which  Christianity  requires.    But  so,  too,  can  Christian 


26      §  3.  EELATION  OF  CHRISTIAN  TO  PHILOSOPHICAL  ETHICS, 

ethics  take  on  philosophic  form ;  for  by  accepting  Christianity 
the  Cliristian  gives  up  no  whit  of  his  rational  nature,  but,  on 
the  contrary,  he  fructifies  and  enriches  it.  The  union  of 
Christian  and  of  philosophical  ethics  is  therefore  to  be 
designated  as  the  goal ;  but  the  way  to  this  union  is  long, 
and  the  attaining  of  this  goal  is  nothing  less  than  the  whole 
of  the  world's  history. 

We  stand  as  yet  in  the  midst  of  this  process ;  and,  in  order 
that  the  union  may  become  real  and  lasting,  it  is  well-advised 
for  us  here  not  to  conceal  and  not  to  multiply  the  differences. 
This  does  not  imply  that  theological  ethics,  until  this  goal  is 
reached,  should  not  seek  to  have  a  strictly  scientific  or 
speculative  character ;  but  it  does  imply  that  both  systems 
should  have  an  independent  position  side  by  side,  so  long  as 
philosophical  ethics  necessitates  and  demands  this.  Further- 
more, so  long  as  a  training  process  to  bring  men  to  Christ  is 
still  necessary,  there  will  be,  even  as  seen  from  the  Christian 
standpoint,  a  place  for  philosophical  ethics ;  so  far  as  it  is 
true,  it  at  least  represents  the  law.  Theological  ethics  should 
readily  allow  to  philosophical  ethics  all  freedom  of  operation, 
yet  without  prejudice  to  the  claim  that  in  Christianity  is  given 
absolute  ethical  truth ;  only  a  free  inward  assent  has  moral 
worth.  Philosophical  ethics  may  also  commend  itself  to 
human  nature  which  prophesies  a  Eedeemer,  although  it  itself 
becomes  no  prophet ;  and  so  it  can  serve  as  a  guide  to 
Christianity,  being  accessible  to  the  universal  consciousness  of 
mankind.  The  progress  of  such  philosophical  ethics  is  there- 
fore to  be  regarded  by  an  intelligent  theology  as  an  advantage 
to  Christian  science.  On  the  other  hand,  theological  ethics 
must  not  contradict  the  natural  moral  cognitions,  which  on 
their  part  form  a  barrier  against  possible  false  conceptions  of 
Christianity.  While  now  both  cultivate  towards  each  other 
such  a  free  independent  relation,  the  alliance  can  become 
sincere  and  firm  on  both  sides — between  the  first  creation  with 
its  capacities  and  its  susceptible  needs,  and  the  second  creation 
with  its  fulness  of  life  and  of  love. 

The  separation  of  the  two  involves  conflict ;  for  the  non- 
Christian  reason  is  still  destitute  of  the  Christian  element,  and 
opposes  it,  since  man  is  inclined  at  every  stage  to  treat  his 
own  mental  world  as  a  complete  whole ;  and  so  it  is  the  work 


eothe's  view  consideeed.  27 

of  Christian  science  to  show  that  the  want  of  the  Christian 
element  is  a  defect  in  philosophy  itself,  and  that  philosophy 
without  Christianity  cannot  he  rounded  off  into  a  perfect 
whole.  On  the  other  hand,  reason,  after  it  has  been  laid  hold 
of  by  Christianity,  is  not  at  once  so  perfectly  cultivated  in  all 
directions,  that  universal  human  reason  cannot  be  partially 
right  in  opposition  to  it.  But  just  by  conflict,  if  the  love  of 
truth  be  not  wanting,  mutual  approach  and  understanding  are 
brought  about.  This  love  of  truth  on  its  theological  side 
makes  advance  in  constant  regeneration  of  itself  by  taking 
more  and  more  perfect  possession  of  everything  belonging  to 
it,  that  is,  of  the  whole  world  of  the  first  creation.  In  this, 
work  theology  has  one  of  the  most  important  levers,  and  one 
of  the  most  efficient,  even  though  often  uncomfortable,  allies, 
in  philosophical  ethics  and  in  the  opposition  which  it  can 
present  to  every  production  that  is  not  perfectly  scientific. 

Note. — Eothe  distiDguishes  between  philosophical  and  theo- 
logical ethics  thus :  For  philosophical  ethics  the  3o?  /xo/  vov 
GTU)  is  the  fact  of  man's  judgment  concerning  himself — cogito 
ergo  sum;  since  man  is  a  microcosm,  all  thoughts  as  such 
are  included  in  him,  and  the  problem  is  to  unfold  the  fact 
of  self-consciousness  into  an  exhaustive  intellectual  system. 
Theological  ethics,  on  the  other  hand,  has  as  its  point  of 
departure  the  theistic  sense,  or  the  ego  as  religious,  and 
requires  that  the  ego  clearly  understanding  itself  should  know 
itself  as  under  the  control  of  God,  from  the  idea  of  whom  as 
the  starting-point  it  then  operates.  But,  we  may  reply,  the 
philosopher  also  can  take  as  his  starting-point  the  theistic 
sense,  inasmuch  as  religion  belongs  to  the  rational  nature  of 
man  in  general,  and  so  of  the  philosopher  also.  Spinoza  and 
other  philosophers  illustrate  this ;  but  the  product  even  in  this 
case  does  not  on  that  account  become  Christian  ethics ;  and 
conversely  a  Christian  ethics  as  such  can  take  as  its  starting- 
point  self-consciousness,  and,  if  this  is  defined  in  a  Christian 
sense,  can  construct  a  system  which  is  really  theological,  but 
which,  according  to  Eotlie,  must  be  called  philosophical. 
Therefore  we  say,  rather,  philosophy  also,  it  is  true,  can  turn 
to  account  the  general  theistic  sense  which  inheres  in  reason, 
and  can,  though  it  usually  indeed  does  not,  produce  a  religious 
ethics.  But  Christian  or  theological  ethics  is  not  possible 
merely  through  the  general  theistic  sense,  but  only  through 
that  sense  as  modified  by  Christianity.  It  is  only  the  Christian 
idea  of  God  from  which,  as  its  premise,  a  Christian  system  of 


28      §  3.  EELATIOX  OF  CHPJSTIAN  TO  PHILOSOPHICAL  ETHICS. 

ethics  can  take  its  starting-point.  This  idea  of  God  is  disclosed 
first  iu  Christianity,  because  tlie  holy  love  whicli  constitutes 
the  Christian  idea  of  God  becomes  truly  manifest  only  through 
the  deed  of  love  ;  the  apprehension  of  God  as  love,  however, 
is  faith.  But  although  faitli  is  designed  for  all,  yet  not  all  men 
have  faith.  If  the  philosopher  embraces  it,  he  loses  nothing 
of  that  which  is  special  to  him ;  but  he  enlarges  his  circle  of 
vision  and  enriches  his  mental  possession ;  for  the  gospel  is 
fitted  and  designed  to  become  the  possession  of  the  rational 
mind,  although  only  through  an  ethical  process.  But  if  the 
philosopher  does  not  embrace  faith,  then  he  has,  of  course,  only 
his  natural  ego  and  the  general  theistic  sense ;  no  one  can 
forbid  his  seeing  how  far  he  can  get  on  with  these.  But  at  the 
same  time  he  has  no  right  to  say  that  only  his  wisdom  is 
philosophical,  and  that  there  is  no  Christian  philosophy.  By 
such  an  assertion  he  would,  as,  e.g.,  H.  Eitter's  celebrated  work 
on  Christian  Philosophy  shows,  involuntarily  restrict  and  im- 
poverish the  realm  of  philosophy  itself.  Tliereibre  we  repeat, 
philosophical  ethics  and  Christian  ethics  are  not  essentially 
different  in  form,  for  both  can  be  specu]ative ;  also,  not  in 
their  substance  as  such,  as  though  the  philosopher  were  neces- 
sarily not  a  Christian  ;  but  only  the  empirical  character  of  the 
philosophy  of  a  given  time  makes  the  separation  of  the  two 
necessary.  So  long,  however,  as  they  are  separated,  a  twofold 
method  is  possible  for  each :  either  to  start  from  human  con- 
sciousness (philosophical  ethics  from  human  consciousness  in 
general.  Christian  ethics  from  consciousness  as  modified  by 
Christianity),  or  from  the  idea  of  God,  either  the  general  idea 
or  the  distinctively  Christian  idea. 

Editor  s  note. — At  this  point  the  author  in  his  lectures  was 
accustomed  to  give  a  survey  of  tlie  history  of  ethics,  but  in  the 
manuscript  which  he  had  dictated  for  the  press  he  omitted  it. 
[The  titles,  etc.,  in  square  brackets  and  some  minor  alterations 
have  been  added  by  the  translator.  The  parts  in  quotation 
marks  are  taken  from  notes  of  the  author.  For  the  remainder 
the  rditor  is  responsible. — Te.] 

Works  on  the  Histoey  of  Ethics. — Schleiermacher,  Grund- 
linicn  ciner  Kritik  dcr  hishcrigen  Bittcnlchre.  Neander,  Ucbcr 
das  Verlidltniss  der  hcllenischen  Ethik  zur  christliclien  ( Wissen- 
schaftlichc  Abliandlungen,  edited  by  Jacobi,  1851).  GeschicJite 
der  christliclien  Ethik,  1864.  De  Wette,  Sittenlehre  (vol.  ii. 
Abtheilung  2,  Lehrhuch  der  christlichen  Sittenlehre),  1833. 
Stfiudlin,  Gcschichte  der  Moralphilosojjhie,  1823.  L.  von  Hen- 
ning,  Eie  Princiincn  dcr  Ethik  in  historischcr  Entivickclung, 
1825.  Wuttke,  Handhuch  der  christliclien  Sittenlehre,  1861, 
vol.  i.  pp.  21-299.    [Christian  Ethics,  translated  by  J.  P.  Lacroix, 


WORKS  ON  THE  HISTORY  OF  ETHICS.  29 

Edinburgh  and  New  York  1873,  vol.  i.]  Wehrenpfennig, 
Die  VerscJiicdenhcit  der  ethischcn  Princifien  lei  den  Hellenen, 
1856.  Maurice,  Moral  and  Metaphysical  Philosophy.  Vol.  i. 
Ancient  Philosophy,  new  ed.  1872.  Eitter,  GeschicMe  der 
Philosophic.  [In  English :  The  History  of  Ancient  Philosophy, 
translated  by  A.  J.  W.  Morrison,  Oxford  1838.]  Zeller,  Philo- 
sophic der  Gricehcn.  [In  English :  A  History  of  Greek  Philo- 
sophy, translated  by  S.  F.  Alleyne,  London  1881.]  Erdmann, 
Geschichte  der  Philosophic.  Brandis,  Handhuch  der  Geschichto 
der  gricchisch-romischcn  Philosophic.  Max  JNIiiller,  Essays,  1869 
[original  English :  Chips  from  a  German  Worlishop\  vol.  ii. 
[G.  H.  Lewes,  History  of  Philosophy  from  Thales  to  Comte,  5th 
ed.  1880.]  Striimpell,  Geschichte  der  griechischen  Philoso- 
p/w'c  (2nd  Abtheilung:  Die  praldische  Philosop)hic,  1854).  I.  H. 
Fichte,  System  der  Ethih,  1850,  1851.  Vol.  i.  is  historical. 
Paul  Janet,  Histoire  de  la  2>hilosophie  morale  et  politique  dans 
I'antiquite  et  Ics  temps  moderncs.  James  JNIackintosh,  Disserta- 
tion on  the  Progress  of  Ethical  Philosophy  [4th  ed.  by 
Whewcll,  1872].  W.  Whewell,  Lectures  on  the  History  of  Moved 
Philosophy,  1862.  Feuerlein,  Die  philosophisclic  Sittcnlehre  in 
ihrcn  geschiclLtlichen  Havptformcn,  2nd  Theil,  1856-59.  Leopold 
Schmidt,  Die  Ethik  der  cdten  Gricehcn,  2  vols.  1862.  Theobald 
Ziegler,  Geschichte  der  Ethih,  vol.  i.  1881,  Vorliinder,  Geschichte 
der  pihilosophischcn  Morcd-  Bechts-  ttncl  Staatslehrc  der  Franzosen 
und  Englilndcr.  Cuno  Fischer,  Geschichte  der  ncueren  Philo- 
sophic, 3rd  ed.  1878-84.  Windelband,  Geschichte  der  neucren 
Philosophic,  2  vols.  1878-80.  Jodl,  Geschiehtc  der  Ethih  der 
neucren  Philosophic,  1882.  Eucken,  Geschichte  und  Kritik  der 
Grundhegriffe  der  Gegenwart,  1878.  Harms,  Philosopliie  seit 
Kant,  1879.  Die  Formen  der  Ethik,  1878.  E.  von  Hartmann, 
Phdnomenolog ie  des  sittlichcn  Beivusstseins,  1879.  Geschichte 
des  Pcssimdsrnus,  1884.  I,  A.  Dorner,  art.  Ethik  in  Herzog's 
Pea  l-cncyklojKidie. 

Gottfried  Arnold,  Erste  Liche,  d.  i.  wahrc  Albildung  der  ersten 
Christen,  1696.  Cf.  Neander's  Dcnkivurdigkcitcn,  1823  sq. 
Jean  Barbeyrat,  Traite  de  Ice  morale  des  Peres  de  Veglise,  1712. 
Ceillier,  Ap)ologie  dc  la  morale  des  Peres,  1718.  Stiiudlin, 
Geschichte  der  Sittcnlehre  Jesu,  4  vols.  1799-1823.  Geschichte 
der  Lehre  von  der  Sittlichkeit  der  Schctusjncle,  vom  Eid,  Gehct, 
Gewissen.  JNIarheinecke,  Allg.  Geschichte  der  Moral  in  den  der 
Bcformcdion  vorangehenden  Zeitcn.  Feuerlein,  Die  Sittcnlehre 
des  Christenthums  in  ihrcn  geschichtlichcn  Hauptformen,  1855. 
Alex.  Schweizer,  Geschichte  der  reformirten  Ethik.  (Studien  und 
Kritiken,  1850.)  Gass,  Zur  Geschichte  der  Ethik,  in  Brieger's 
Zcitschrift,  i.  ii.  Optimismus  und  Pessimismns,  1876.  Die  Mystik 
des  Nicol.  Cahc(silas.     Geschichte  der  christlichcn  Ethik,  i.  1881. 


30  §  3.  WORKS  ON  THE  HISTORY  OF  ETHICS. 

H.  J.  Bestmann,  GescMchtc  clcr  diristlidien  Sitte,  1880.  Niedner 
in  his  KirchcngescMcMc,  §  81,  106,  120-126,  150,  179,  193. 
From  the  Eeformation  on  §  213,  249,  251,  254.  Also  Eothe, 
Vorlcsungen  ilher  Kirchengeschichte,  eel.  Weingarten. 

Monographs. — Hildebrand,  Gescldchte  und  System  dcr  Bcclits- 
und  Staatsphilosophie,  vol.  i.,  describing  classical  antiquity. 
Jul.  Walter,  Lehrc  von  dcr  praktischen  Vernunft  in  der  griech- 
ischen  Fhilosophie.,  Jena  1874.  Zeller,  Vortrdge  und  Abhand- 
lungen,  vol.  i.  {Pythagoras,  Dcr  Platonischc  Staat.).  Blass,  Die 
attische  Beredsamkcit,  1868. — On  Heraclitus:  'BQi:nQ.yii,Heraclitea. 
Hcraklitische  Studien  in  the  Bhcinische  Museum,  new  series,  vii. 
90-116.  Lassalle,  Die  Philosophic  HeraMit  des  Dunheln  von 
Dphesus,  1858.  Schuster,  HeraMit  von  Ephesus.  Schleier- 
macher,  Werke,  iii.  2.  Heyder,  Ethices  Pythagorem  vindicia. 
Lortzing,  Die  cthischen  Fragmcnte  Dcmokrit's.  Friedrich  Liibker, 
Die  sophokleische  Theologie  und  Ethik,  1851-55.  Beitr'dge  zur 
Ethik  imd  Theologie  des  Euripides,  1863.  Harpf,  Die  Ethik  des 
Protagoras,  1884. — On  Socrates :  Schleiermacher,  iii.  2.  287  sq. 
Brandis,  Bhcinisches  Museum,  i.  188,  ii.  85.  Also  Luzac,  Wiggers, 
Delbriick,  Dissen,  v.  Lasaulx.  [Jan  Luizac,  Zectiones  Atticce, 
De  Aiya/xia  Socratis  dissertatio,  1809.  Oratio  de  Soerate  cive, 
1796.  Gustav  Fr.  Wiggers,  Sokrates  als  MenscJi,  Bilrger,  und 
Philosoph,  2nd  ed.  1811.  Part  of  it  in  English :  A  Life  of 
Socrates,  translated  from  the  German  by  W.  Smith,  London  1840. 
(In  same  vol.  Life  of  Socrates,  by  Diogenes  Laertius,  in  Greek, 
and  Schleiermacher,  On  the  Worth  of  Socrates  as  a  Philosopher, 
translated  by  C.  Thirlwall.)  Fr.  Fer.  Delbriick,  Sokrates, 
Betrachtungcn  und  Untersuchungen,  Cologne  1819.  Ludolf 
Georg  Dissen,  De  pihilosophia  7norali  in  Xenopihontis  de  Socrate 
commentariis  tradita,  Gottingen  1812.  Ernst  v.  Lasaulx,  Des 
Sokrates,  Lcbcn,  Lchrc,  imd  Tod,  etc.,  Munich  1857.]  Siebeck, 
TJcher  Sokrates  Verhdltniss  zur  Sophistik,  1873. — On  Plato : 
Schleiermacher's  translation,  with  introductions.  [In  English  : 
The  Apology  of  Socrates,  the  Crito,  and  part  of  the  Phmdo, 
with  Schleiermacher's  introductions,  and  his  essay  On  the  Worth 
of  Socrates  as  a  Philosopher,  1863.]  Also  translation  by  Miiller, 
with  introductions  by  Steinhart.  Koppen,  Politik  nach  ])lato- 
nischcn  Grimdsdtzcn,  1818.  Bechtslehre,  1819.  Van  Heusde, 
Lnitia  philosophic^  Platonicce,  1827-31.  Bonitz,  Platonischc 
Studien,  2nd  ed.  1875.  Carl  F.  Hermann,  Vindiciarum  Plato- 
nicarum  lAhelli  Duo,  1840.  Die  historischen  Elemente  des  plato- 
nisehcn  Stacdsideals,  1849.  Gesehichtc  und  System  der  plato- 
nischen  Philosophic,  1839.  Also  Susemihl,  Munk,  Krohn,  and 
others.  [Franz  Susemihl,  Prodromus  plcdoniseher  Forsehungcn, 
Gottingen  1852.  Die  genctische  EntiDichelimg  der  platonischcn 
Philosophic,  Leipzig  1855-50.     Ed.  Munk,  Die  naturliche  Ord- 


WOKKS  ON  THE  HISTORY  OF  ETHICS.  31 

nung  dcr  flatonischen  Schriftcn,  Berlin  1857.  August  Krohii, 
Die  plato7iische  Frage,  Halle  1878.  Studien  zur  sohratisch- 
jjlatonischen  Litcratur,  Halle  1876.]  Baur,  Das  Christliche  dcs 
Platonismus,  oder  Sokrates  und  Christus.  (Edited  by  Zeller : 
drei  Ahhandlungen  zur  Geschichte  dcr  alten  Philosopliie,  1876.) 
Stuhr,  Voiii  Staatsleben  nach  jJiatoniscJien,  aristotelischen,  und 
christlichen  Grundsdtzen,  1850.  Kretzschmar,  Der  Kavipf  dcs 
Plato  icm  religiose  iind  sittlichc  Principicn  dcs  Stctatslchens,  1852. 
GYivadejyDe  Platonis  principiis  ethicis,  1865.  Justi,  Die  asthct- 
isclien  Elemente  in  der platonischen  Philosophic,  1860.  Von  Stein, 
Geschichte  des  Platonismus.  Michelis,  Die  Philosophic  Platds, 
2  vols.  1859-60.  Teichmiiller,  Die  Peihenfolge  dcr  plcdonischcn 
Dialoge,  1879.  Wildauer,  Die  Psychologic  dcs  Willcns  hei 
Sokratcs,  Plato,  Aristoteles,  1879.  [English  works  :  W.  Whewell, 
The  Platonic  Dialogues  for  English  Beaders  (Cambridge  1859- 
61).  TJic  Dialogues  of  Plato,  translated,  with  analyses,  etc.,  by 
B.  Jowett,  5  vols.  Oxford  1875.  The  Bcpublic  of  Plato,  trans- 
lated by  J.  L.  Davies  and  D.  J.  Vaughan,  3rd  ed.  Cambridge 
1866.  Plato  and  the  other  Companions  of  Sokrates,  by  George 
Grote,  3  vols.  2nd  ed.  London  1867.] — On  Aristotle:  Schleier- 
macher,  Ueher  die  ethischen  Werke  des  Aristoteles,  AVerke,  iii.  3. 
306  sq.  Ueher  die  gricchischcn  Scholicn  zur  Nikom.  Ethik,  iii. 
2.  309  sq.  Adolf  Stahr,  Aristotelia,  1830-32.  Brandis,  UcUr 
die  Schicksalc  der  aristotelischen  Bilcher  (Bhein.  Mus.  i.  236  sq.). 
Spengel,  TJchcr  die  nnter  dcm  Namcn  des  Aristoteles  erhaltencn 
ethiscJmi  Schriftcn  (Ahh.  der  hair.  Akad.  der  Wissensch.  1841, 
vol.  iii.).  Bernays,  Aristoteles'  Politik  uhersctzt,  1872.  Biese, 
Die  Philosophic  des  Aristoteles.  Bonitz,  Aristotelische  Studien. 
Wortcrhuch  zu  Aristoteles.  Trendelenburg,  Herhart's  praktische 
Philosop>hic  und  die  Ethik  der  Alten,  in  the  Ahhandlungen  dcr 
Berliner  Akad.  1856.  Also,  Historischc  Beitrdgc  zur  Philosophic, 
vol.  ii.  iii.  {Der  Widerstreit  zwischen  Kant  und  Aristoteles  in 
der  Ethik,  vol.  iii.  p.  171  sq.  Zur  aristotelischen  Ethik,  vol. 
iii.  p.  399  sq.,  vol.  ii.  p.  352  sq.  Nothiocndigkcit  und  Freihcit 
in  der  griechischen  Philosophic,  vol.  ii.  p.  112  sq.).  Sir  A. 
Grant,  The  Ethics  of  Aristotle  [Greek,  with  copious  English 
notes  and  essays,  4th  ed.  London  1885].  Hartenstein,  Ris- 
torisch-philosophische  Ahhandlungen :  Ueher  den  ivisscnschaft- 
lichcn  Wcrth  der  Ethik  dcs  Aristoteles,  p.  340  sq.  Matthies, 
Die  platonischc  und  die  aristotelische  Staatsidee,  1848.  J.  Lom- 
VLi&tzs,ch,Quomodo  Plato  et  Arist.  religionis  ac  reipuhlica3 p)rineipicc 
conjunxerint,  1863.  Teichmiiller,  Aristotelische  Forschungcn, 
2  vols.  1867-69.  Die  Einhcit  der  aristotelischen  Eudamonie. 
Bulletin  de  la  classe  cle  sc.  historique  de  V Academic  des  sc.  dc 
Petershourg,  xvi.  1859.  Ncilc  Studien  zur  Geschichte  dcr  Begriffe, 
1879.      (Heft    3,    Die   praktische     Vernunft    hei    Aristoteles.) 


32  §  3.  WORKS  ON  THE  HISTOKY  OF  ETHICS. 

Ueberweg,  Ucbcr  das  Aristofelische,  Kantischc,  Hcrhartische 
Moralprincip.  (Fichte's  Zcitschrift,  vol.  xxiv.  1854,  p.  71  sq.) 
Eucken,  Ucber  die  Mcthodc  und  Grundlagcn  der  Ethik  des  Ai^is- 
toteles,  1870.  A.  C.  Bradle.y,  Siaatslehrc  des  Aristotelcs,  transl. 
"by  Immelmaun,  1884.  [The  original:  Aristotle s  Conception 
of  the  State,  1880.]  Hildebrand,  Die  Stellung  des  Aristotelcs 
zmn  Dctcrminismus  und  Indcterminismus,  1884.  W.  M.  Hatch, 
Moved  Philosophy  of  Aristotle,  1879.  Bernays,  Tlicophrast'' s 
Sclirift  ither  die  Frdmniigkcit.  [English  Works  :  The  Nie.  Ethics 
of  Aristotle,  mainly  from  the  text  of  Bekker,  translated  by 
D,  P.  Chase,  4th  ed.  Oxford  1877.  Also  a  translation  by 
F.  H.  Peters,  London  1881.  The  Politics  of  Aristotle,  trans- 
lated, with  introductions,  notes,  and  indices,  by  B.  JoM^ett, 
1885.  Tlie  Politics  of  Aristotle,  translated  by  J.  E.  C.  Welldon, 
London  1883.  Aristotle,  by  Geo.  Grote,  edited  by  Alex.  Bain 
and  C.  G.  Eobertson,  2nd  ed.  London  1880.] — On  the  Stoic 
Philosophy:  M.  Heinze,  Sloicorum  de  affectihus  doctrina,  1861. 
Diehl,  Zur  Ethih  des  Stoilxrs  Zeno,  Programm,  1877.  Baur, 
Seneca  imd  Paulus,  das  Verhdltniss  des  Stoicismus  zuin  Chris- 
tenthum  (edited  by  Zeller:  Prei  Abhandlungcn,  etc.,  1876). 
Waldstein,  Einfluss  des  Stoicismus  auf  die  dlteste  christliche 
Zchrhildung  (Studicn  und  Kritiken,  1880,  iv.).  Weygoldt,  Philo- 
sophie  dcr  Stoa,  1883.  \Scnccas  Works,  translated  by  Thomas 
Lodue,  London  1614.  Seneca's  Morcds  hy  way  of  Abstract,  bv 
Pt.  L'Estrange,  London  1793 ;  Hartford,  Conn.,  1807.  F.  W. 
Farrar,  Seekers  after  God,  Sunday  Library,  vol.  iii.  London 
1868.  Bishop  Lightfoot,  Essay  on  St.  Paul  and  Seneca  (in 
Commentary  on  Epistle  to  the  Phili2)pians).  W.  T.  Jackson, 
Seneca  and  Kant,  Dayton  0.  1881.  W.  W.  Capes,  Stoicism, 
London  1880.] — On  Epicurus :  Guyau,  La  Morcde  cV Epicure. 
Gompertz,  Neue  Bruchstucke  Epikurs,  bcsonders  ilber  die  Willens- 
frage  (Akademie  der  Wisscnschaften,  Vienna  1876,  No.  5). 
Von  Gizycki,  Ueber  das  Lcbcn  und  die  Morcdpihilosophie  des 
Epiknr,  1880.  Heinze,  Euddmonismus  in  der  griechischen 
Philosophic,  1883.  [Epicurus  s  Morals,  faithfully  Englished  by 
Walter  Charleton,  London  1670.  Also  a  translation  by  J. 
Digby,  newly  edited  by  J.  Tela,  London  1822.  W.  Wallace, 
Epicureanism,  London  1880.]  —  On  Plutarch:  Moller,  Pie 
Pcligion  Plutarch's,  1881.  0.  Greard,  La  morale  de  Plutarquc. 
Volkmann,  Lcbcn,  Schriften,  und  Philosophic  des  Plutarch  von 
Chdronca,  2nd  ed.  1872.  W.  Mueller,  Ethices  Plotiniancc  linect- 
mcnta,  1867.  [Plutarch's  Morcds,  translated  from  the  Greek 
by  several  hands  ;  corrected  and  revised  by  W.  W.  Goodwin, 
with  an  introduction  by  E.  W.  Emerson,  Boston  1870. 
Hellenica :  A  Collection  of  Essays  on  Greek  Poetry,  Philosop)hy, 
History,   and    Religion,   edited    by    Evelyn    Abbott,    London 


WORKS  ON  THE  IIISTOEY  OF  ETHICS.  33 

1880.  Diogenes  Laertius,  The  Lives  and  Opinions  of  Eminent 
Fhilosophcrs,  translated  by  C.  D.  Yonge,  London  1853.] — 
On  Philo's  Ethics  :  Wolff,  Philos.  Monatshcfte,  Bd.  xv.  [  Worlc^ 
of  Philo  Judceus,  translated  by  C.  D.  Yonge,  Bohn's  Eccl. 
Library,  1854-55.] — On  Old  Testament  Ethics :  Oehler,  Theo- 
logie  des  alien  Testaments,  2nd  ed.  1882.  [In  English:  Theology 
of  the  Old  Testament,  translated  by  Ellen  D.  Smith  and  Sophia 
Taylor,  1874:  T.  and  T.  Clark]  Schultz,  Alttcstamentlichc 
Thcologie,  2nd  ed.  1879.  Jarrel,  Old  Testament  Ethics,  2nd  ed. 
1883. — Yrie.6\^\\(\.QX,Darstellungcn  aus  der  Sittengeschichte  Boms, 
3  vols.     Keim,  Horn  und  das  Christcnthuin,  ed.  Ziegler,  1881. 

Thoma,  Geschichtc  der  christlichen  Sittcnlehrc  in  der  Zeit  des 
neuen  Testaments,  1879.  Ernesti,  Die  Ethih  des  Ajjostel  Paulus, 
ord  ed.  1880.  Weitzsiicker,  Die  Anfdnge  christlicher  Sittc 
{Jahrh.  filr  deutsche  Thcol.  187G,  Heft  1).  Zockler,  ^yii!isc/ic 
(reschichte  der  Askesc.  Uhlhorn,  Die  christlichc  Liclcsthdtigkcit, 
2  vols.  [2ud  ed.  1884.  Vol.  i.  translated  by  S.  Taylor,  Christian 
Charitg  in  the  Ancient  Charch,  1883].  Huber,  Fhilosophie  der 
Kirclioivdtcr. — On  Justin  :  Semisch  [Justin  der  Mdrtyrer,  1840]. 
Engelhardt,  Das  Christcnthum  Justin  des  Ifdrtyrers,  1878. — On 
Montanism  :  Schwegler  [Der  Montanismus  unci  die  christliche 
Kirclie  des  zwciten  Jahrhunderts,  1841].  Eitschl,  Altkatliolische 
Kirchc,  2nd  ed.  1857.  Belck  [Geschichtc  des  Montanismus'], 
1883.  Bonwetsch  [Gesch.  des  Montanismus],  1882.— E.  E.  liede- 
penuing,  Origcnes,  1841.  IMehlhorn,  Origenes'  Lehre  von  der 
Frciheit,  in  Brieger's  Zeitschrift  fur  historische  Theologie,  vol.  ii. 
Er.  Jul.  Winter,  Ethik  des  Clemens  von  Alexandrien,  1882. 
Th.  Forster,  Amhrosius,  Halle  1884.  A.  Dorner,  Augustin, 
pp.  295  sq.,  308  sq.,  323  sq.  Eeuter,  Geschichtc  der  Aufklarung 
im  Mittelcdter.  Werner,  Alcuiii  und  sein  Jalirhundert.  Baur, 
Die  christliche  Kirche  im  Mittelcdter.  Plitt,  Der  hcilige  Bernard, 
A)isehauungcn  vom  christlichen  Lchen,  in  Niedner's  Zeitschrift, 
1862,  p.  194  sq.  C.  August  Hase,  Franz  von  Assisi,  1856. 
[Sir  James  Stephen,  St.  Francis  of  Assisi,  in  Essays  in  Eccl. 
Biography,  vol.  i.  4th  ed.  I860.]  Eemusat,  Abdlard.  Braun, 
De  F.  Ahcelardi  Ethica.  Deutsch,  Abdlard.  Bittcher,  Die 
Schriften,  der  p)hilosop)hische  Standpunkt,  tmd  die  Morcd  des  P. 
Abdlard  (Zeitschrift  filr  historische  Theologie,  1870).  Werner, 
Thomas  von  Aqiiin.  [E.  B.  Vaughan,  The  Life  and  Labours  of 
S.  Thomas  of  Aejuin,  1871-72.]  Jourdain,  La  Philosophic  de 
Thomas.  Eietter,  Die  Morcd  des  heiligen  Thomas.  Baumann, 
Die  Staatslehre  des  Thomas,  1873.  JDic  klassische  Moral  des 
jYcdholieisnms  {Fhilosophische  Monrdsheftc,  xv.  p.  449  sq.).  On 
Tliomas  Aquinas's  theory  of  virtue  :  Neander  in  the  Wissen- 
schaftliche  Abhandlungcn,  edited  by  Jacob!,  1851.  On  Duns 
Scotus :   A.    Dorner    in    Herzog's    Becdencyclopddie,    2nd   ed. 


34  §  3.  worjvs  ox  the  history  of  ethics. 

Ullmann,  Ilcformatorcn  vor  der  Mcformation.  [In  English : 
Beformers  heforc  the  JReformation,  translated  by  E.  Menzies, 
T.  &  T.  Clark,  1855.]  Lechler,  Johann  von  Widif,  1873.  [In 
English  :  .loltn  Wydiffc  and  Ids' Englisli  Precursors,  translated  by 
P.  Lorirner,  Eel.  Tract  Soc,  London,  new  ed.  1884.]  Wilhelm 
Preger,  Gesdddite  der  dcutsclicn  Mystik,  1874.  Sclnvab,  Johann 
Gcrson.  On  Eckart :  Lasson  [Meister  Ecldiart  der  Mystil'er, 
1868].  Martensen  [Meister  Eckart,  from  the  Danish,  1842, 
new  Danish  ed.  1851]. — Engelhardt,  Richard  von  Sand  Victor 
und  Joh.  Buyshrock.  Liebner,  Hugo  von  Sand  Victor.  Eitschl, 
Die  christliehc  Lehre  von  der  Bechtfcrtigung  und  Versoh- 
nung,  vol.  i.  2nd  ed.  1882.  [In  English :  A  Critical  History 
of  the  Christian  Doctrine  of  Jnsiifcation  and  Beconeiliation, 
translated  by  J.  S.  Black,  Edinburgh  1872.]  G-eschichte  dcs 
Pictismus,  2  vols.  Luthardt,  Die  Ethih  Luther's  in  ihren 
Grundziigen,  1867.  Lommatzsch,  Zitther's  Lehre  vom  cthisch- 
religiosen  Standpirnkt.  Lobstein,  Ethik  Ccdvin's.  Herrlinger, 
Die  Thcologic  Mdccnchthons.  Luthardt,  Mdanehthons  Arhciten 
im  Gehiet  der  Moral,  1884. — On  Thomas  Venatorius :  Schwarz 
in  Studien  und  Kritiken,  1850.  On  Lambert  Daneau:  P.  de 
Felice  [Lanihcrt  Daneau  .  .  .  .  sa  vie,  ses  ouvragcs,  ses  lettres 
inedites],  1881.  Henke,  Georg  Calixtus  tmd  seine  Zeit,  1853. 
[Abstract  of  the  foregoing  by  C.  M.  Mead  in  the  Bihliotheca 
Sacra,  1865.]  On  the  history  of  Pietism,  c£  Nippold,  Studien 
und  Kritiken,  1882,  p.  347  sq.  Sachsse,  Ursprung  und  Wesen 
des  Pictismus,  1884. 

Zeller,  Geschichtc  der  dcutschcn  Pldlosophie.  V.  Cousin, 
Histoire  de  Ice  Philosophic  morcde  au  18  sihclc,  1839-42.  Leslie 
Stephen,  History  of  English  Tho^ight  in  the  Eighteenth  Century, 
1876.  E.  B.  Hartung,  Grundlimcn  einer  Ethik  hei  Jordano 
Bruno,  1878.  F.  M.  Heinze,  Sittcnlehre  des  Descartes,  1872. 
Sigwart,  Spinoza's  kurzcr  Traktcd  von  Gotf,  dem  Mensehcn  und 
dessen  Glilckseligkeit,  1870.  Avenarius  \_Ud)cr  die  heiden  ersten 
Phasen  dcs  spinozischcn  Pantheismus],  1868.  Theodor  Camerer 
[Die  Ldire  Spinoza's,  1877].  I*aul  Wilholm  Schmidt  [Spinozct 
und  Schleiermacher],  1868.  [W.  II.  White,  Spinoza's  Ethic, 
translated,  London  1883.]  Frederick  Pollock  \^Spinoza,  his 
Life  and  Philosoj^hy,  1880.  James  Martineau,  A  Study  of 
Spinoza,  2nd  ed.  1883].  Mayer,  Tliomas  Hohhes,  Darstdlung 
und  Kritik  seiner  philosop)hisehen,  staatsreehtliehen  und  kirchen- 
politisehen  Ldiren,  1883.  Winter,  Darlcgung  unci  Ivritik  der 
Loekeschen  Lehre  vom  empirischcn  Ursprung  der  siftlichen 
Grundsdtze,  1884.  E.  Tagart,  Locke's  Writings  and  Philosoijhy, 
1855.  Cuno  Fischer,  F.  Bacon  und  seine  Nachfolger,  2nd  ed. 
1875  [Fischer's  earlier  work,  Franz  Baco  von  Vendam,  Die 
Becdphilosophie  und  ihr  Zeitcdter,  1856,  was  translated  by  J. 


"WOEKS  ON  THE  HISTORY  OF  ETHICS.  35 

Oxenford  under  the  title,  Francis  Bacon  of  Vcrulam,  Bcalistic 
Fhilosophy  ami  its  Age  (with  appendices),  London  1857].  E. 
Pfleiderer,  A.  G-eulinx  ah  I-Iau2Jtvcrtreter  der  ohhasionalistischen 
Mctaphysik  tmd  MJiik  [2nd  ed.  1882].  Gopfert,  Geulinx  cthisches 
System,  1883.  E.  Ptleiderer,  Fmjnrisinus  unci  SIccjms  lei  Hume. 
Von  Gizycki,  Die  Ethik  Hume's,  1878.  Zimmermann,  Ucher 
Hicmc's  cnqnrische  Bcgrunclung  der  Morcd,  1884.  [J.  D.  Morsll, 
Historiccd  and  Criticcd  View  of  the  Speculcdive  Fhilosophy  of 
Europe,  2nd  ed.  1847.]  Lechler,  GcschicMc  des  englischen 
Beismus,  1841. — Eeuchlin,  GeschieJite  von  Bort-Boycd  [1839-44. 
Sir  J.  Stephen,  Tlie  Bort-Boyalists,  in  Essays  in  Ecel.  Biogr. 
vol.  i.].  On  the  Jesuits  :  Pascal,  Bettres  a  un  Frovineicd.  [In 
English  :  TJte  Frovineicd  Letters  of  Blaise  Fasccd,  Glasgow  1851  ; 
another  translation  (in  "  The  Golden  Library  "),  London  1875  ; 
another,  edited  by  J.  de  Soy  res,  1880.]  Perrault,  Morcdc  des 
Jesuitcs,  3  vols.  16G7,  1702.  [In  English  :  The  Jesuits  Morcds, 
1670.  Sir  J.  Stephen:  The  Founders  of  Jesuitism,  I.e.  vol.  i.l 
Crome,  Fragmatische  Geschichte  der  Monchsorden,  1774-83,  vols, 
ix.  and  x.  Ellendorf,  Die  Moral  und  Folitik  der  Jesuiten,  1840. 
Gieseler,  Kirchcngeschichtc,  vols,  iii.,  and  v.  p.  42  sq.  [In 
English :  A  Text-book  of  Church  History,  translated  by  S. 
Davidson,  revised  and  completed  by  H.  B.  Smith,  !N"ew  York 
1868.]  Semisch,  Der  Jesiiiienorden,  1870.  Steitz,  article  Jesuiten 
in  Herzog's  Becdcneyelopddic.  Also  Wagenmann  in  Palmer's 
Fddagogischc  Eneyclopddic.  A.  Keller,  Die  Moraltheologie  des 
Fater  Chtry,  2ud  ed.  1869.  Haiiess,  Jesuitenspiegel.  [Stewart 
Pose,  Igncdius  Boyola  and  the  Early  Jesuits,  London  1871. 
W.  C.  Cartwright,  Tlie  Jesuits,  their  Constitution  and  Teachiruf^ 
London  1876.] — Hejipe,  Geschichte  der  ciuietistischen  Mystik. 
Thomas  Fowler,  Shaftcshury  and  Huteheson,  1882.  Von  Gizycki, 
Die  Fhilosophie  SJuiftcslury's,  1876. — On  the  Scottish  School  : 
M'Cosh,  Tlie  Scottish  Fhilosophy,  1875. — On  Leibnitz :  Trende- 
lenburg, Beitrdge,  vol.  ii.  p.  188  sq.  Zimmermann,  Das 
Bechtsprincip  lei  Leibnitz,  1852.  Pichler,  Die  Thcol.  des  Leib- 
nitz, 1869.  Caspari  [Leihnitz'  Fhilosophie  heleuchtet  vom 
Gesichtspunkt  der  physikcdischen  Grundhegriffe  von  Lvraft  und 
Stoffl  1870.  E.  Pfleiderer  [G.  W.  Leibnitz  als  Fatriot,  StacUs- 
mann  unci  Bildungstrdger,  etc.],  1870. — On  his  Optimism : 
G.  Jellinek  \_Die  Weltanschauung  en  Leibnitz  und  Schopen- 
hauer s,  ihre  Griinde  und  ihre  Berechtigung'],  1872.  Engler, 
[Darstellung  u.  Kritik  d.  Leibnitzisehen  Optimismus'],  1883. 
Leon  Olle-Laprune,  La  philosoflvie  de  Mcdchranche.  Eoseukranz, 
Diderot's  Leben  und  Werke,  1866. — On  Voltaire:  Strauss  {Vol- 
taire, scchs  Vortrdge,  3rd  ed.  1872.]  Bungener  \_Voltaire  et  son 
Temps,  1851.  In  English :  Voltaire  and  his  Times,  Edinburgh 
1854].  —  Zeller,    Ueber  decs  Kantische   Moralprincip   und   den 


36  §  3.    WOEKS  ON  THE  HISTORY  OF  ETHICS. 

Gegcnsatz  formcdcr  und  materialcr  3foraIprincipien,  1879. 
{Vortrdge,  vol.  iii.  1884,  p..  156  sq.)  Meurer,  Das  Ver- 
hdltniss  dcr  Kantischen  U7ul  Schiller  schen  Ethik,  1880.  A. 
Dorner,  Uebcr  die  Principien  dcr  Kantischen  UthiJc,  1875. 
Lelimann,  Uehcr  Kcmfs  Frincijncn  der  Uthik  und  Schopen- 
hauer's Beurthcilung  dcrselbcn,  1880.  Eoljert  Adamson  [On 
the  Philosophy  of  Kant^,  German  trans,  by  Schaarsclimidt. 
Cantoni,  Umanuele  Kant,  vol.  ii.  Zct  piltilosophia  Pratiea. — 
On  Fichte  :  Harms,  Ahhandhmgen  zur  systcmatischen  Philo- 
sophic, p.  277  sq.  A.  Lasson  [Fichte  im  Vcrhdltniss  zur 
Kirclie  und  Stcud,  1863]. — On  Schleiermacher :  Hartenstein, 
Pic  Principien  der  Schl.  Philosojjhie.  Schaller  \_Vorlcsungen 
iiber  Schleiermacher,  184-4].  Strauss  [Per  Christies  des  Glauhens 
und  der  Jesus  der  Gcschichtc,  einc  Kritik  des  Schleier- 
macher schen  Lehcns  Jcsu,  1865].  Weissenborn  [Vorlcsungcn 
uher  Schleiermacher  s  Dialcktik  und  Dogmatik,  1847].  Schenkel 
[F.  Schleiermacher,  ein  Lehcns-  tmd  Charcdderbdd,  1868]. 
Twesten,  Pinleitung  zur  philosop)hischen  Pthik,  1841,  and 
Zur  Prinncrung  an  Schleiermacher,  1869.  Vorliinder,  SchVs 
Sittenlchre,  ausfiihrlich  dctrgcstclltundheurfhcilt,  1851.  Dilthey, 
Pas  Lehen  Schl.  vol.  i.  Bender,  TJicologie  Schl.  1878.  [Painze, 
Schleiermacher' s  Glauhenslehre  in  ihrcr  Ahhdngigkcit  von  seiner 
Pldlosopihie,  etc.,  1877.] 

Modern  moralists:  "From  Kant's  school  emanated:  The 
Eationalistic  moralists,  Joliann  Wilhelm  Schmid  [Uebcr  den 
Geist  dcr  Sittenlchre  Jesii.  und  seiner  Apostel,  1790]  and  Carl 
Christian  Erhard  Schmid  [Versuch  ciner  MorcdphUosophie,  1802] 
and  Krng,  Lehrhuch  dcr  ehristl.  Sitte.  The  Supernaturalistic 
moralists:  Staudlin  [Philosop)hi$che  und  hihlische  Morcd,  1805], 
von  Ammon  [Handhuch  dcr  ehristl.  Sittenlchre],  in  three 
volumes,  full  of  anecdotes,  1823-29,  and  Vogel,  with  a  leaning 
towards  Jacobi  [Henrich  Vogel,  Pie  Philosophie  des  Lehcns  der 
Natur  gcgcnilhcr  den  hishcrigcn  speeidatiren  unci  Naturp)hilo- 
sophien,  1845]. — Opponents  of  Kant :  Eeinhard,  Pie  christlichc 
Morcd,  5  vols.  1788-1815,  containing  much  ethical  material 
with  fine  moral  judgment,  following  Wolff's  doctrine  of  per- 
fection. Also  von  Flatt  [Pricfe  uber  den  onorcdischen  Erkennt- 
nissgrund  dcr  Pcligion  nbcrhaupt,  und  hcsonders  in  Pezichung 
anfdie  kantischc  Philoso2')hie,  1789.  Vorlesungen  Uher  christlichc 
Morcd,  1823].  Berger  [Pie  Sittenlchre  des  nc7icn  Testaments 
(Theil  4  of  his  Einleitung  in  das  N.  T.),  1797-1800].  Eepre- 
sentatives  of  the  Jacobi-Fries  school :  De  Wette,  Sittenlchre, 
4  vols.  1819-23,  Klister,  Baumgarten-Crusius  "  [Lehrhuch  der 
christlichen  Sittenlchre,  1826]. 

From  the  school  of  Hegel,  wlio  in  his  Pcchtsp)]iiloso'phie  also 
treated  of  ethics,  proceeded :  "  Daub,  Christliclic  Morcd,  3  vols. 


WORKS  ON  THE  HISTORY  OF  ETHICS.  o  / 

1840-41.  Marlieineke,  System  der  christliclien  Moral,  1847. 
Somewhat  more  of  Schleiermacher's  influence  is  seen  in  Wirtb, 
System  der  Ethik,  2  vols.  1841.  Martensen,  Grundriss  des 
Systems  der  ^forcdjyJiilosojyhie,  1841.  H.  Merz,  System  der  christl. 
Sittenlehre  in  seiner  Gestedtung  nach  den  Grundsdtzen  des  Protes- 
tantismvs  im  Gegensatze  zum  Kcdholicismifs,  1841." 

"  To  Schleiermacher's  school  belong  :  Eiitenick,  who  compiled 
a  popular  work  on  Christian  ethics  [Der  christliehe  Glauhe, 
Theil  2  also  with  the  title,  Sittenlehre],  2nd  ed.  1841.  Wyss, 
Vorlesungen  uher  das  Iwchste  Gut.  Gelzer,  Die  Religion  irti 
Leben  oder  die  christliehe  Sittenlehre,  1839.  Jiiger,  Die  Grund- 
legriffe  der  ehristlieJien  Sittenlehre,  1856,  has  made  some  just 
strictures  upon  Schleiermacher. — NitzscVi  in  his  system  imites 
dogmatics  and  ethics  from  the  Biblical,  as  Sartorius  {Die  h. 
Liehe,  ord  ed.)  from  the  Lutheran,  point  of  view.  [Nitzsch, 
System  der  christlichen  Lehre.  In  English  :  System  of  Ch.  Doct., 
trans,  from  the  5th  German  ed.  by  R  Montgomery  and  J.  Hennen, 
Edinburgh  1849.  Sartorius,  Die  Lehre  xon  der  heiligen  Liehe, 
4th  ed.  18G1.  In  English:  The  Doetrine  of  Divine  Ijore,  trans, 
by  S.  Taylor,  1884.]  Schwarz,  too,  a  friend  of  Schleiermacher, 
treated  Evangelical  P^thics  as  a  branch  of  the  general  doctrine 
of  the  kingdom  of  God."  [Schwarz,  Handhueh  der  evangelisch- 
chrisilichen  Ethik,  1821  ;  2nd  ed.  with  the  title,  Die  Sittenlehre 
des  cvang.  Christenthums  cds  Wissensehaft,  1830.] 

"  Bruch,  Lchrhuch  der  christl.  Sittenlehre,  1829-32.  —  Of 
Neander's  school :  Bohmer,  System,  des  christlichen  Lebcns  nach 
seiner  Bejahung,  Verneinunij,  Wiederherstelhmg  wissensch.  dargc- 
stellt.  Erom  the  Lutheran  point  of  view,  besides  Sartorius  : 
Harless,  Christl.  Ethik,  1842  [7th  ed.  1875.  In  English  :  System 
of  Christian  Ethics,  trans,  by  A.  W.  Morrison  and  W.  Eindlay, 
1868],  condensed  in  form  and  rich  in  thought,  but  confined 
to  too  narrow  limits  (freedom  not  treated  particularly ;  in 
the  sphere  of  objective  things  only  the  preservation  of  sav- 
ing grace  is  taken  into  view).  Hofmann,  Schrifthevxis,  ii.  2. 
p.  263.  He  makes  ethics  the  delineation  of  the  essence  of 
Christian  conduct,  i.e.  he  views  morality  from  the  point  of 
view  of  moral  exercise.  The  genesis  of  the  moral  disposition 
is  not  treated,  but  only  the  manifestation  of  the  Christian 
possession  of  the  disposition,  in  virtues  and  in  communities 
[Hofmann's  Thcolocjische  Ethik  was  published  in  1878.  Ed.]. 
Wuttke,  Handhueh  der  ehristliehen  Sittenlehre,  1861,  2  vols. 
[In  English :  Christian  Ethics,  New  York,  Nelson  &  Phillips, 
1873],  makes  large  use  of  Eothe  and  Schleiermacher,  but 
makes  little  acknowledgment  of  his  obligation.  Vilmar's 
Thcologisehe  Morcd,  1871,  is  good  in  its  delineation  of  sins  and 
vices   and   their   ramifications.     Bernhard   Weudt,  Kirchliehe 


38  §  ;J.    WORKS  ON  THE  HISTOHY  OF  ETHICS. 

Etliik  vom  Standpunli  dcr  christlichcii  Frciheit.  The  title  of 
the  second  part  is :  Das  Reich  Gottes  unci  das  Reich  der  Welt,18Q5. 
Cullmann,  Die  christlichc  Ethik,  2  vols.  1864-66,  treats  ethics 
from  a  theosophic  standpoint.  Alex,  von  Oettingen,  Moral- 
statistik,  of  which  the  second  part  constitutes  a  Christlichc 
Sittcnlchre,  1873,  3rd  ed.  1882,  outlines  a  system  of  social 
ethics.  He  occupies  himself  with  the  important  problem,  how 
human  freedom  can  be  harmonized  with  statistics.  His  solu- 
tion is,  that  man's  freedom  is  by  nature  dependent  on  the  race, 
and  that  the  power  of  sin  preponderates,  being  subject  to  a 
course  fixed  by  law.  Christianity  alone  breaks  through  the 
natural  law  of  sin.  The  co- working  of  the  race  and  of  the  weak 
freedom  which  existed  before  Christianity  explains,  he  thinks, 
the  statistical  regularity  of  the  manifestations  of  sin  in  the 
domain  of  nature.  IMartensen,  Die  christliche  Ethih,  All- 
gemeiner  Theil,  3rd  ed.  (Specieller  Theil,  Die  inclividuelle  und 
die  socicde  Ethik),  1878  [cf.  my  notice  in  the  Jahrhilcher  fiir 
deutsche  Thcologie,  1818.  Ed.].  [In  English:  Christian  Ethics, 
translated  from  the  original  Danish  by  C.  Spence,  1873  ;  Chris- 
tian Ethics,  translated  from  the  German  by  W.  Affleck,  1881, 
both  published  by  T.  &  T.  Clark,  Edinburgh.]  Chr.  Er.  Schmid, 
Christlichc  Sittciilchrc,  edited  by  Heller,  1801,  is  one  of  the  best 
works,  especially  thorough  in  laying  the  foundations.  [In 
English  :  Gcnercd  Principles  of  Christian  Ethics,  first  part  of 
Schmid's  work  trans,  and  abridged  by  AV.  J.  Mann,  Phil.  1872.] 
Eothe,  Theologischc  Ethik,  3  vols.  1845-48,  2nd  ed.  1867,  2 
vols.  (Holtzmann  added  to  the  two  volumes  of  the  new  edition 
[prepared  by  Rothe  himself]  the  remainder  according  to  the 
first  edition) ;  lie  is  since  Schleiermacher  the  most  original 
moralist."  J.  P.  Lange,  Grundriss  der  christl.  Ethik,  1878. 
Hermann  Weiss,  Die  christl.  Idee  des  Giden,  1877.  0.  Pfleiderer, 
Grundriss  der  Glaubens-  und  Sittcnlchre,  2nd  ed.  1882.  H.  L. 
J.  Heppe,  Christl.  Ethik,  edited  by  Kuhnert,  1882  [published 
at  the  same  time,  with  the  historical  section  omitted,  under  the 
title,  Christliche  Sittcnlclirc~\.  J.  T.  Beck,  Vorlcsunrjcn  ilhcr 
christl.  Ethik,  1883,  2  vols.  ed.  Lindenmeyer.  Frank,  System 
der  christl.  Sittlichkeit,  vol.  i.  1884. 

"  Modern  philosophical  moralists :  Stahl,  Die  Philosophic  des 
Rechts,  in  2  vols.  2nd  ed.  1845,  theologically  deduced,  but 
unsatisfactory  in  its  treatment  of  principles.  Hartenstein, 
Die  Grundhegriffe  der  ethischcnWisscnschaftcn  (Herbartiau),  1844. 
Chalybiius,  System  dcr  speculcdivcn  Ethik,  2  vols.  1850.  After 
his  statement  of  principles  (phenomenology  of  ethics),  he  treats 
of  eudremonology,  the  doctrine  of  right,  and  religious  ethics. 
Trendelenburg,  Ncdurrccht  auf  clem  Grunde  der  Ethik,  1860 
[2nd  ed.  1868].    I.  H.  Fichte,  System  der  Ethik,  2  vols.  1850-53. 


WOUKS  ON  THE  HISTOEY  OF  ETHICS.  39 

Calderwood,  HamVoooh  of  Moral  Philosophy,  1872  [7th  ed.  1881]. 
A.  Leitch,  Ethics  of  Theism :  a  Criticism  and  its  Vindication, 
Edin.  1868." — Schuppe,  Grundziigc  dcr  Ethik  und  Bechtsphilo- 
sophic,  1881.  Seydel,  Ethilc  odcr  Wissenschaft  vom  Sein  Sollendcn 
(disciple  of  Weisse),  1874.  Von  Havtmanii,  Fhdnomcnologie  dcs 
sittlichen  Ecvmsstseins,  1879.  Baumanii,  Handhuch  dcr  Moral, 
nchst  eincm  Atriss  dcr  Rcchtsphilosophic,  1879.  H.  Lotze, 
Grundziigc  dcr  praktischen  Philosophic,  1882  [2nd  ed.  1884. 
In  English :  Outlines  of  Practiced  Philosophy,  translated  and 
edited  by  Prof.  G.  T.  Ladd,  Boston  1885].  Bergmann,  Uchcr 
das  Piichtigc,  Erortcrung  der  cthischen  Grundfragen,  1883. 
Fliigel,  Prohlcme  der  Philosophic  unci  ihrc  Losungcn,  2nd  Theil, 
187C.  Ziller,  AUgcmcinc  ■philosoiohischc  Elhih  (Herbartian), 
1880. — Works  treating  ethics  from  the  standpoint  of  empiricism : 
Von  Gizycki,  G-rundziige  dcr  3Ioral,  1883.  Herbert  Spencer, 
Thcdsaclicn  dcr  Ethik,  translated  into  German  by  Vetter  [Orig. 
English  :  Tlic  Data  of  Ethics],  1879.  Carneri,  Grundlegung  der 
Ethik,  1881.  Leslie  Stephen,  The  Science  of  Ethics,  1882. 
Guyot,  Zee  Morcde,  1883. 

Catholic  moralists :  "  In  the  18th  and  19th  centnries  the 
ethics  of  Catholic  as  well  as  Protestant  writers  was  shaped 
by  the  philosophical  systems.  Following  Wolff's  philosophy 
there  were:  Stadler  [Mo^rdische  Grundsdtze,  1791]  and  Schwai'z- 
htiber  [System  der  christlichcn  Sittenlchre,  1794].  Following 
Kant :  Hermes  [Einleitung  in  die  christkatholisrlic  Tlicolocgic, 
1819],  Braun,  Vogelsang  \LehrljUch  dcr  christlichcn  Sittenlchre, 
1834-39],  Elvenich  [Die  Morcdphilfjsop)hie,  1833].  Following 
Fichte :  Geishiittner  [Thcologischc  Morcd,  1805].  Following 
Schelling:  Cajetan  von  Weiller  [Tugend  die  hochstc  Kunst, 
181()].  Thoughtful,  moderate,  and  pious  are  tlie  works  of 
Michael  Sailer  (Handhuch  der  christlichcn  Morcd,  1834), 
Hirscher,  Christliche  Mored,  1851.  More  strictly  Catholic, 
yet  not  Jesuitic,  but  Thomistic,  is  Werner's  System  dcr  christ- 
lichen  Ethik,  in  3  vols.  1850-53." — Stapf,  Christliche  Moral, 
1841.  Schwane,  Spczicllc  Morcdtheologie,  1878.  Linsemann, 
Lehrhuch  der  Morcdtheologie,  1878  (influenced  by  Moiiler).  E. 
Mliller,  Theologia  moralis,  4th  ed.  1883.  Lehmkuhl,  Theologia 
morcdis,  vols.  i.  ii.  1884.  Gury,  Casus  conscicnticc,  1881.  Com- 
pendiuni  thcologicc  morcdis,  1881  (Jesuitic). 

[The  following  additional  English  and  American  works  on 
ethics  may  also  be  named ;  but  no  attempt  is  made  to  give  a 
list  complete  either  in  number  or  in  analysis. 

Hugo  Grotius,  Dc  jure  belli  ac  pads  lihri  tres  (1625,  later  ed. 
1751),  in  Latin  with  abridged  translation,  3  vols.,  and  in  English 
alone,  1  vol.,  Grotius  on  the  Bights  of  War  and  Peace,  by  W. 
Whewell  (Cambridge  1853).     Francis  Bacon,  Advancement  of 


40  §  3.    WORKS  ON  THE  HISTORY  OF  ETHICS. 

Learning  (1605).  Do.  M'itli  Bacon's  Essays  (in  Beeton's  Books 
for  all  Time,  1874).  Thomas  Hobbes,  Leviathan  (1651,  re- 
printed, Oxford  1881).  Moml  and  Political  Works  (1750). 
Englisli  Works,  ed.  by  Sir  AVm.  Molesworth  (1839-45).  Opera 
Fhilosophica,  ed.  by  Molesworth  (1839-45).  Ptalph  Ciidworth, 
The  True  Lntellectual  System  of  the  Univei'se  (1st.  ed.  1678),  with 
a  treatise  on  Eternal  and  Lmmutahle  Morality,  and  with 
Moslieim's  notes  and  dissertations  translated  by  J.  Harrison 
(London  1845).  Tlie  Ethical  Works  of  Ecdph  Cudworth:  a 
Treatise  on  Free  Will,  edited  by  J.  Allen  (London  1838). 
Henry  More,  Enchiridion  Ethicum,  p7weip2ca  Moralis  Philo- 
sophic rudimenta  co7}iplectens  (1669,  new  ed.  1695).  Eichard 
Cuinberland,  De  Legihics  Naturm  (1672).  A  Philosopihical 
Lnquiry  into  the  Laws  of  Nature  (1750).  John  Locke,  Essay 
on  the  Human  Understandmg  (1690,  32nd  ed.  1860.  New 
ed.  World  Library  of  Standard  Works,  Ward,  Lock,  &  Co., 
London  1881).  Samuel  Clarke,  A  Demonstration  oftlic  Being  and 
Attributes  of  God  (London  1705,  8th  ed.  1732).  A  Discourse  con- 
cerning the  Unchangeable  Ohligcdions  of  jSfaturcd  Pel igio7i  (London 
1706,in  Watson's  collection  of  Theol.  Tracts,  1791).  Shaftesbury, 
Characteristics  of  Men,  Manners,  Ojnnions,  Times  (1711,  5th  ed. 
1773.  New  ed.  by  W.  M.  Hatch,  London  1870).  Bernard  de 
Mandeville,  The  Fable  of  the  Bees ;  or,  Private  Vices  Public  Benefits 
(1714,  9th  ed.  1755,  Edinburgh  1772).  William  Wollaston, 
The  Religion  of  Ncdure  Delinccded  (1725,  8th  ed.  1759).  Joseph 
Butler,  The  Analogy  of  Peligion,  eic.  (1736.  Numerous  editions 
have  been  published,  of  which  may  be  mentioned  that  of  the 
Eeligious  Tract  Society,  London  1881,  edited  by  J.  Angus,  which 
also  includes  fifteen  of  Butler's  sermons).  Bishop  Butler's 
Ethiced  Discourses,  prepared  as  a  text-book  in  IMoral  Philosophy 
by  Dr.  Whewell,  edited  by  J.  C.  Passniore  (Philadelphia  1855v 
Both  these  include  Jyutiev'sDisscrtatio^i  on  the  Nature  of  Virtue). 
George  Berkeley,  A  Treatise  concerning  the  L\inciples  of  LIuman 
Knowledge  (1734).  New  edition  with  prolegomena  and  annota- 
tions by  C.  P.  Krauth  (Philadelphia  1874).  Francis  Hutcheson, 
A  System  of  Moral  Philosophy  {Vloo).  David  Hartley,  Observa- 
tions on  Man  (1749,  5th  ed.  1810,  London).  David  Hume, 
Treatise  of  Human  Ncdure  1739.  The  Philosophical  Works  of 
David  Hume,  edited  by  T.  H.  Green  and  T.  H.  Grose  (London 
1874).  PJchard  Price,  A  Pevicw  of  the  Principal  Questions  and 
Difficulties  in  Morals  (1758,  3rd  ed.  1787).  Adam  Smith,  Theory 
of  the  Moral  Sentiments  (1759,  12th  ed.  1809).  Works,  edited, 
with  a  life  of  the  author,  by  Dugald  Stewart  (London  1812). 
Essays,  Philosophical  and  Literary  (World  Library,  etc.,  London 
1880).  Joseph  Priestley,  The  Doctrine  of  Philosophical  Necessity 
Illustrated  (London  1777).     Disquisitions  relcding  to  Mcdtcr  and 


WOEKS  ON  THE  IIISTOBY  OF  ETHICS.  41 

Spirit  (including  the  foregoing,  2nd  ed.  Birmingham  1782). 
Worhs,  edited  by  J.  T.  Eutt  (London  1817-31).  Jonathan 
Edwards,  Two  Dissertations :  I.  Concerning  the  End  for  u-Jiich 
God  created  the  World ;  II.  The  Ncdure  of  True  Virtue  (Boston 
1765,  Edinburgh  1788).  On  Freedom  of  Will  (Boston  1754). 
Works  (London  1817,  Edinb.  vols.  ix.  x.  1847,  New  York  1879). 
William  Paley,  Principles  of  Moral  and  Political  Philosophy 
(1785).  The  Morcd  Philosophy  of  Paley,  with  notes  and  disserta- 
tions by  Bain  (1852,  Chambers's  Instructive  and  Entertaining 
Library).  Paley's  Morcd  Philosojihy,  with  annotations  by  Eichard 
Whately  (London  1859).  Jeremy  Bentham,  An  Introduction 
to  the  Principles  of  Morals  and  Lcr/islatioii  (London  1789,  new  ed. 
1823,  Oxford  1876).  Thomas  Eeid,  Essays  on  the  Active  Powers 
of  the  HuwMn  Mind  (1788).  TFo^'/.'-s,  edited,  with  notes,  disser- 
tations, etc.,  by  Sir  William  Hamilton  (Edinburgh  1846-63). 
Dugald  Stewart,  The  Philosophy  of  the  Active  and  Moral  Powers 
of  Man  (Edinburgh  1828).  Works,  edited  by  Sir  W.  Hamilton 
(1854-58).  Tliomas  Brown,  Lectures  on  the  Philoso2}Jiy  of  the 
Human  Mind  (1820).  Do.  with  Ijcctures  on  Ethics,  and 
preface  by  T.  Chalmei'S  (20th  ed.  London  1860).  James 
Mill,  Analysis  of  the  Phenomena  of  the  Human  Mind  (1829). 
Do.  with  notes  by  A.  Bain,  A.  Findlater,  and  Gr.  Grote  ;  edited 
by  J.  S.  Mill  (London  1869).  S.  T.  Coleridge,  The  Friend 
(1812).  Do.  new  edition,  revised  by  D.  Coleridge  (London 
1863).  Aids  to  Pieflection  (1825).  Do.  edited  by  D.  Coleridge 
(7th  ed.  1854).  Do.  edited  by  T.  Fenby  (London  1873). 
Works,  edited  by  W.  G.  T.  Shedd  (Xew  York  1853,  reprinted 
1884).  Jouffroy,  Introduction  to  Ethics,  translated  from  the 
French  by  W.  H.  Channing  (Boston  1838).  Francis  Wayland, 
Elements  of  Moral  Science  (1835,  95th  thousand,  Boston  1868). 
Jonathan  Dymond,  Essays  on  the  Principles  ofMorcdit)/  (London 
1829,  4th  ed.  1842  and  1851).  Ealph  Wardlaw,  Christian  Ethics 
(London  1833,  5th  ed.  1852).  William  Whewell,  The  Elements 
of  Morality  (1845,  4th  ed.  Cambridge  1854).  L.  P.  Hickok,  A 
System  of  Morcd  Science  (Schenectady  1853).  Do.  revised  with 
the  co-operation  of  J.  H.  Seelye  (Boston  1880).  Joseph  Haven, 
Morcd  Philosophy  (Boston  1859).  Archibald  Alexander,  Outlines 
of  Morcd  Science  (New  York  1852,  new  ed.  1876).  Mark  Hopkins, 
Lectures  on  Moral  Seiencc  (Lowell  Institute  Lectures,  Boston ;  New 
Y^ork  1862,  new  ed.  1870).  The  Law  of  Love,  cmd  Love  as  a 
Law  (New  York  1869,  revised  ed.  1881).  John  Stuart  Mill, 
Utilitarianism  (London  1863  2nd  ed.  1864).  Pissertations 
and  Discussions  (particularly  on  Bentham,  vol.  i.,  and  Dr. 
Whewell  on  Moral  Philosophy,  vol.  ii.  London  1859).  E.  H. 
Gillett,  God  in  Human  Thought  (New  York  1874).  The  Moral 
System  (New  York  1874).     Alexander  Bain,  Mental  and  Moral 


42  §  4.    METHOD. 

Science  (London  1868,  3rd  ed.  1872).  TJie  Emotions  and  the 
Will  (1859,  3rd  ed.  1875).  F.  D.  Maurice,  The  Conscience: 
Lectures  on  Casuistry  (London  1868,  2nd  ed.  1872).  Henry 
Sido-wick,  The  Methods  of  Ethics  (London  1874,  3rd  ed.  1884). 
J.  H.  Fairchild,  Morcd  Philosophy ;  or,  the  Science  of  Obligation 
(New  York  1869).  C.  G.  Finney,  Systematic  Theology,  particu- 
larly the  part  on  Moral  Government  (Oberlin,  Ohio  1878,  edited 
bv  J.  H.  Fairchild).  Kant's  Theory  of  Ethics,  translated  by 
T.  K.  Abbott  (1873).  Third  edition  under  the  title,  Kanfs 
Critique  of  Practiced  Reason,  and  other  WorJcs  on  the  Theory  of 
Ethics  (London  1883).  T.  11.  Birks,  Si'perncdural  Eevelation  ;  or, 
First  Po-ioiciples  of  Morcd  Theology  (London  1879).  E.  G. 
Eobinsou,  The  Eelations  of  Moral  Law  to  Science  and  to  Religion 
(Boston  1881).  Stanley  Leathes,  The  Foundcdions  of  Morcdity, 
lieini:;  Discourses  on  the  Ten  Commandments  (London  1882). 
F.  Pollock,  Essays  in  Jurisjyrudence  and  Ethics  (London  1882). 
T.  H.  Green,  Prolegomena  to  Ethics  (Oxford  1883).  Wm.  Arthur, 
Eifference  Ictivccn  Physiccd  and  Morcd  Law  (Fernley  Lecture, 
London  1883).  Paul  Janet,  Theory  of  Morals,  translated  by 
Mary  Chapman  (New  York,  C.  Scribner's  Sons,  1883).  James 
Martineau,  Types  of  Ethiccd  Theory  (London  1885).  Noah 
Porter,  Elements  of  Morcd  Science  (New  York,  C.  Scribner's  Sons, 
1885).     Kant's  Ethics  (Chicago  1886). 

Historical:  Ilobert  Blakey,  History  of  Morcd  Science  (2nd  ed. 
1836,  Edinburgh).  W.  E.  H.  Lecky,  History  of  Eurojjcan 
Morals  (1869,  "3rd  ed.  1877).  Henry  Sidgwick,  article  on 
Ethics  in  the  Encyclopedia  Britannica,  9th  ed.  Also  Out- 
lines of  the  History  of  Ethics  (London  1886).  John  Stuart 
Blackie,  Four  Phases  of  Morals  :  Socrcdes,  Aristotle,  Christianity, 
Utilitarianism  (Edinburgh  1871). 

On  Biblical  morals :  C.  A.  Ptow,  Tlie  Morcd  Teaching  of  the 
New  Testament  (London  1872).  J.  A.  Hessey,  Morcd  Difficulties 
:onnectecl  with-  the  Bible  (l>oyle  Lectures,  1871).  J.  W.  Haley, 
Examination  of  Alleged  Discrepancies  of  the  Bible  (Andover, 
Mass.  3rd  ed.  1876).  J.  H.  Jellett,  An  Examination  of  sovie 
of  the  Moral  Difficulties  of  the  Old  Testament  (Dublin  1867). 
Newman  Smyth,  The  Morcdity  of  the  Old  Testament  (1887).] 

§  4.    Method. 

The  immediate  source  of  knowledge  for  Christian  ethics  is 
the  mind  enlightened  by  Christianity  ;  standing,  therefore, 
in  inward  accord  with  the  Bible,  and  regulating  itself  .by 
it ;  educated,  moreover,  by  the  Church  and  by  the  history 
of  the  moral  sentiments  of  the  Church.     The  material 


THE  SOUKCE  OF  ETHICAL  KNOWLEDGE.  43 

given  by  this  source  of  knowledge  is  to  be  brought 
into  systematic  form,  in  which  the  classification  shall 
correspond  to  the  divisions  of  the  subject  as  objectively 
presented. 

1,  It  was  recognised  originally  that  the  Christian,  through 
the  Holy  Spirit,  has  in  himself  an  independent  source  of 
ethical  knowledge  in  harmony  with  the  doctrine  of  Christ  and 
the  apostles,  which  was  at  first  transmitted  orally.  Yet  this 
did  not  involve  a  sharp  definition  of  its  limits  as  over  against 
non-Christian  teachings  of  philosophy  or  morals,  and  especially 
did  not  secure  it  against  spiritualistic  extravagances  such  as 
showed  themselves  in  Gnosticism  and  the  beginnings  of  a  self- 
mortifying  asceticism.  The  fixing  of  the  canon  and,  in  con- 
nection with  it,  the  organization  of  the  Church  in  episcopal 
and  synodal  form  put  a  check  upon  caprice,  it  is  true,  but 
only  too  quickly  was  Christianity  transformed  within  the 
Church  into  a  nova  lex,  a  new  sort  of  legal  religion.  This 
degeneration  increased  after  the  synods  arrogated  to  them- 
selves, with  reference  to  both  dogmatics  and  ethics,  a  right  of 
legislation  under  divine  authority ;  and  the  hierarchy  in  the 
Middle  Ages  ruled  the  consciences  and  the  moral  conceptions 
of  men  by  means  of  the  confessional. 

By  the  Reformation  immediate  access  to  the  Bible,  yes,  to  God 
Himself,  even  without  a  mature  ethical  knowledge,  was  restored, 
and  the  Christian  conscience  reinstated  in  its  rights.  Yet 
frequently  a  new  legal  position  was  taken,  the  principle  of 
faith  not  being  sufficiently  used  as  a  means  of  promoting 
ethical  knowledge  ;  and  therefore  individual  assurance  of  the 
intrinsic  truth  of  the  things  recommended  by  Biblical 
authority  was  too  little  cultivated.  Furthermore,  the  prin- 
ciple of  the  Eeformation  at  first  spread  its  clear  light 
predominantly  only  upon  the  inward,  personal  side  of  ethics. 
The  relation  to  the  worldly  side  remained  still  fluctuating 
and  unsatisfactorily  defined,  since  rather  only  the  getting  and 
keeping  of  salvation  through  faith  and  sanctification  was 
looked  at  as  one's  ethical  duty.  On  the  other  hand,  the  duty 
was  neglected  of  leavening  the  whole  world  of  the  first 
creation  with  the  Christian  spirit,  and  thereby  building  up  a 
temple  in  mankind  which  comprehends  every  department  of 


44  §  4.    METHOD. 

morals :  the  individual,  marriage  and  the  family,  social,  civil, 
and  political  life,  art,  science,  and  the  Church.  The  view  of 
things  became  broader  and  freer  by  means  of  the  philosophical 
movement  beginning  with  Kant,  which,  to  be  sure,  at  first 
hostilely  opposed  Christian  ethics  as  well  as  dogmatics,  but 
turned  agaiu,  especially  through  Schleiermacher's  influence, 
towards  religion  and  Christianity.  More  recently  theological 
ethics  recognises,  as  a  source  of  ethical  knowledge,  Christian 
experience  or  faith,  and  the  Bible,  i.e.  the  material  and  the 
formal  aspects  of  the  evangelical  principle. 

2.  That  universal  human  reason  by  itself  cannot  be  a 
source  of  knowledge  for  Christian  morality,  is  plain  from  what 
has  been  already  said  of  the  relation  between  natural  and 
Christian  ethics.  On  the  other  hand,  however,  ethics  is  no 
historical  science ;  it  is  neither  a  part  of  Biblical  theology  nor 
of  symbolics,  but  a  positive  science,  and  as  such  has  for  its 
province  to  set  forth  Christianity  as  the  truth,  and  to  show 
the  grounds  of  it.  Therefore  no  merely  external  authority, 
however  venerable,  can  be  the  immediate  source  of  know- 
ledge for  it ;  not  the  Holy  Scriptures,  still  less  the  Church. 
The  material  given  by  the  Church  and  by  the  sacred  Scriptures 
must  first  be  appropriated  spiritually,  i.e.  in  faith,  before  it 
can  be  systematically  stated.  Christianity  requires  that  men 
come  to  a  knowledge  of  its  truth  through  faith  (John  viii. 
31,  32),  and  so  to  a  union  of  reason  and  of  Christianity,  which 
is,  to  be  sure,  at  first  of  an  ethico-religious  sort,  but  which  must 
be  capable  of  being  developed  into  scientific  certainty.  Just 
in  the  department  of  ethics  it  is  of  especial  importance  to  hold 
faithfully  to  the  Christian  doctrine  of  the  Holy  Spirit,  who 
gives  personal  knowledge,  because  otherwise  even  the  sacred 
Scriptures  could  not  be  rightly  understood.  This  is  shown  in 
Church  history  by  the  numerous  errors  whose  origin  is  due  to 
a  literal  instead  of  a  spiritual  apprehension,  e.g.  of  the  Sermon 
on  the  Mount.  Furthermore,  to  that  Christian  good  which  it 
is  the  part  of  morality  to  attain  belongs  also  the  implanting  of* 
a  moral  knowledge  and  judgment  of  one's  own  (Heb.  v.  14; 
Eom.  xii.  2) ;  for  the  ethical  is  willed  perfectly  only  when  it 
is  willed  as  that  Avhicli  is  in  itself  good,  because  willed  by 
God.  But,  in  order  to  this,  one  must  use  his  own  knowledge 
as  the  light  of  the  will.      Wisdom  is  a  part  of  the  actualized 


THE  BIBLE  AS  AN  AUTHORITY  IN  ETHICS.  45 

Christian  good  itself.  Suppose  an  external  authority  enjoined 
the  right  and  the  good ;  still  if  one  did  not  recognise  it  as 
what  is  in  itself  good  and  divine,  then,  at  best,  he  would  come 
to  a  legal  obedience ;  but  this  is  not  as  yet  that  which  is  good 
in  the  Christian  sense. 

3.  Nevertheless  in  theological  ethics  the  Bible  has  a 
radically  important  place ;  it  is  to  the  Cliristian  an  authority, 
— not  merely  an  outward  one,  however,  but  an  inward  one. 
He  is  inwardly  bound  to  it  by  the  bond  of  reverential  love. 
He  finds  in  it,  in  the  circle  of  the  apostles  and  prophets, 
his  spiritual  home,  his  vital  element ;  for  faith  itself,  born 
of  the  word  and  the  Spirit,  is  an  espousal  with  the  sacred 
Scriptures,  which,  through  the  Holy  Ghost,  become  again 
living  in  man.  Moreover,  faith  is  no  finished  thing,  so  that, 
if  only  it  once  exist,  it  always  continues  of  itself  according  to 
the  law  of  inertia,  as  it  were ;  rather,  it  continues  only  by 
means  of  perpetual  reproduction,  in  daily  self-renewal,  by  use 
of  the  same  means  which  served  to  originate  it.  Then,  too,  it 
is  an  unfinished  thing  in  the  further  sense,  that  it  is  as  yet 
continually  imperfect,  and  is  in  need  of  growtli,  which  is 
effected  by  more  and  more  incorporating  into  one's  fibre  the 
contents  of  the  Scriptures.  The  original,  objective  Christianity, 
as  it  lies  before  us  in  the  canon  and  is  to  be  set  forth  by 
Biblical  theology,  as  the  science  of  the  contents  of  tlie  canon, 
remains  at  every  stage  the  norm,  which  must  not  be  con- 
tradicted by  that  which  wishes  to  pass  for  Christian  morality. 
On  the  other  liand,  .since  ethics,  like  eveiy  science,  is  a 
progressive  one,  it  is  only  natural  that  the  ethical  contents  of 
Scripture,  which  Biblical  theology  presents  historically,  should 
at  a  given  period  not  be  exhausted  by  our  knowledge ;  and  so 
also  that  the  same  ethical  idea,  later,  in  other  relations,  should 
have  to  seek  another  form  of  expression  than  at  the  outset. 

To  the  Old  Testament  belongs  an  authority  mediated  and 
conditioned  by  the  New.  If  ethics  includes  the  origin  of 
morality,  and  does  not  merely  presuppose  that  origin,  then 
the  Old  Testament,  the  Law  and  the  Prophets,  acquires  a 
permanent  significance ;  for  it  indicates  negatively  and  posi- 
tively the  normal  progress  towards  Christian  morality,  partly, 
to  be  sure,  in  national  Israelitish  form.  But  in  this  very 
respect  two  things  are  noteworthy.      On  the  one  hand,  it  is 


46  §   4.    METHOD. 

a  divinely  purposed  limitation  of  the  Old  Testament,  that 
religion  clothed  in  national  form  is  in  the  theocmcy  intimately 
interwoven  with  the  State,  from  which  limitation  the  catholicity 
of  Christianity  would  hold  itself  free.  But,  on  the  other  hand, 
there  is  in  the  Old  Testament  also  something  already  made 
actual,  A'vhich  in  the  New  forms  a  problem  to  be  solved  only 
gradually,  namely,  a  national  life  slui'ped  hy  the  'princvplc  of 
■religion.  In  this  respect  there  is  in  the  Old  Testament 
something  typical,  something  which  in  Christianity  could  not 
at  the  outset  exist.  The  Old  Testament,  in  this  respect,  has 
yet  to  await  a  resurrection  in  transfigured  Christian  form. 
Especially,  too, '  the  history  of  the  Old  Testament,  as  well 
as  the  law,  contains  in  this  relation  a  wealth  of  guiding 
suggestions.  For  the  rest,  it  is  indeed  to  be  said  that  nothing 
in  the  Old  Testament  could  stand  unmodified  in  the  New, 
that  everything,  even  the  Decalogue,  has  in  the  New 
Testament  a  new  sort  of  validity  (Matt.  ix.  IG  ;  Heb.  xii.  26; 
cf.  Hag.  ii.  7).  On  the  other  hand,  it  should  be  said  that  of 
the  revelation  in  the  Old  Testament  nothing  is  lost,  but  that 
in  Christianity  it  has  no  termination  other  than  its  completion 
or  its  fulfilment. 

4.  In  the  Church,  so  far  as  it  is  led  by  the  Holy  Spirit,  we 
see  the  developments  of  the  morality  of  primeval  canonical 
Christianity,  not  without  many  aberrations  (as  we  know 
indeed),  so  that  the  Church  can  no  more  serve  as  an 
immediate  source  of  knowledge  for  ethics  than  for  dogmatics. 
But  an  enlightened  faith,  in  harmony  with  the  sacred 
Scriptures,  and  governed  by  them,  serves  as  the  critical 
element  over  against  ecclesiastical  morality,  and  is  able  to 
make  Christian  morality  secure.  With  this  restriction  the 
other  side  must  also  be  taken  into  view.  In  Christendom 
there  is  an  evolution  of  Christianity ;  the  Church  possesses 
Avisdom  and  works  of  wisdom  which  it  is  essential  as  a  means 
of  culture  to  contemplate.  As  dogmatics  must  not  disregard 
the  work  of  framing  doctrines  which  has  been  accomplished 
by  the  Church,  and  act  as  though  before  now  nothing  had  been 
done,  so,  too,  ethical  knowledge  is  a  common  work  of  the 
Church ;  and  every  moralist  who  enters  upon  it,  should  be 
exempt  from  the  fancy  that  he  is  to  begin  from  the  very  com- 
mencement.    For   every  one  who  wishes  to  take   part,  as  a 


AUTHOKITY  OF  THE  CHUKCII  IN  ETHICS.  47 

member,  in  this  history  of  the  evolution  of  the  truths  of  the 
Church  must  he  simply  a  member.  But  further,  ethics  in 
general,  as  well  as  its  single  departments,  has  a  variable  side, 
and  we  must  work  for  the  present  time.  To  the  present 
duty  one  is  equal  only  in  case  he  knows  what  already  exists 
of  the  kingdom  of  God,  and  what  does  not.  Isolation  from 
the  social  life  of  the  Church  would  engender  eccentricities, 
which  through  intercourse  with  others  would  be  worn  off. 
In  general,  ethics,  even  more  than  dogmatics,  has  immediate 
reference  to  society.  This  necessary  relation  of  ethics  to  the 
Church  implies,  finally,  that  theological  ethics  cannot  over- 
look the  difference  of  confessions,  especially  between  the 
Evangelical  and  the  Eoman  Catholic.  The  doctrine  already 
laid  down  concerning  the  source  of  knowledge,  and  con- 
cerning authority  and  law,  places  us  on  tlie  Protestant  side ; 
but  no  less  also  does  the  ethical  subject-matter. 


THE  SYSTEM   OF   CHRISTIAN   ETHICS. 


§  5.  Sijllahus, 

The  fundamental  objective  knowledge  contained  in  the  faith 
of  a  mind  enlightened  through  Christianity  is,  primarily, 
knowledge  of  God,  and  is  consequently  of  a  dogmatic 
character ;  but  as  knowledge  of  the  ethical  God,  or  of  the 
aboriginally  moral  Being,  it  is  at  the  same  time  the 
source  of  the  true  knowledge  of  morality  in  the  world, 
which  forms  the  proper  subject  of  ethics./  From  the 
ethical  God,  as  He  is  made  known  to  faith  l>y  the  whole 
system  of  the  facts  of  revelation,  morality  in  the  world, 
and  therefore  also  Christian  ethics,  has  its  scientific 
point  of  departure.  Now  in  order  to  get  a  knowledge 
of  Christian  morality,  it  is  needful,  first,  to  present 
everything  that  serves  theoretically  and  practically  to 
establish  it ;  and,  secondly,  to  set  forth  how  Christian 
morality  has  been  unfolded,  or  has  branched  out  into 
the  kingdom  of  Christian  good.  Hence  Christian 
ethics,  as  derived  from  the  idea  of  God,  is  divided  in  the 
following  way : — 

A.  Starting-point :  The  ethical  idea  of  God  as  found  iu  the 

enlightened  Christian  spirit.      (Lemmas  borrowed   from 
Dogmatics.) 

B.  Topical  Arrangement  of  the  System. 

I.  Foundation ;  or  the  divinely -ordained  ideal  and  real 
2werc(iuisites  for  the  realization  of  the  ethical  end  for  which 
the   world  was  made,  i.e.  of  the  kingdom  of  God  ;  and  the 


THE  DESCRIPTIVE  AND  THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  METHOD.         49 

process  by  which  a  moral  world  comes  into  being.     [Things 
presupposed  in  Christian  morality. — Ed.] 

II.  The  development  of  Christian  morality  into  the  wealth 
of  good  which  is  found  in  Christianity,  or  in  the  kingdom  of 
God.      Special  ethics.     The  world  of  Christian  good. 

1.  If  it  be  acknowledged  that  we  are  called  upon  to  recognise 
the  intrinsic  truth  and  necessity  of  Christian  morality,  then 
the  system  of  ethics  must  be  connected  with  the  Christian 
idea  of  God.  This  may  seem  unnecessary,  if  one  has  in 
view  Schleiermacher's  Christliche  Sittc,  or  the  psychological 
method  which  is  so  common,  and  which  especially  suits  a  wide- 
spread taste  of  the  times.  Schleiermacher  treats  the  subject 
in  a  purely  descriptive  way ;  lie  aims  to  portray  the  existing 
ethico-Christian  world,  its  excellences,  its  virtuous  forces,  its 
conduct.  What  he  calls  the  expansive  action  of  man  also 
exhibits,  it  is  true,  the  conquest  of  the  world  by  the  Holy 
Spirit ;  but  the  history  of  mankind,  as  it  is  raised  from 
elementary  beginnings,  through  the  stage  of  law,  up  to  the 
stage  of  Christian  morality,  is  not  j)ortrayed.  As  contrasted 
with  a  merely  imperative  legal  form  of  ethics,  the  descriptive 
has  certainly  the  advantage  that  it  indicates  that  morality 
does  not  exist  merely  in  the  form  of  obligation,  but,  since 
Christ's  time,  also  in  the  form  of  reality.  But  if  ethics  is  to 
be  not  merely  an  empirical  or  historical  science,  if  it  seeks 
rather  to  answer  the  longing  of  the  conscious  Christian  mind 
to  apprehend  the  intrinsic  truth  and  necessity  of  moral  good,, 
then  we  cannot  stop  with  a  merely  descriptive  form  of  ethics.. 
Furthermore,  Schleiermacher  does  not  depict  the  origin  of 
Christian  morality  and  the  regeneration  of  the  individual,  but 
only  presupposes  them.  We,  too,  in  our  treatment  of  ethics, 
assume  Christian  faith  as  already  existent ;  but  we  assume- 
this  in  such  a  way  that  the  very  task  is  put  upon  us  of 
learning  how  this  faith  in  form  and  substance  is  justified. 

The  psychological  method  may  seem,  now,  to  accomplish 
this  end,  in  that  it  describes  the  moral  constitution,  freedom, 
and  conscience,  and  the  normal  development  of  that  constitu- 
tion, and  yet  in  doing  this  at  the  same  time  proceeds  genetically. 
Yet  merely  seeing  the  genesis  of  a  thing  does  not  involve 
seeing  its  intrinsic  truth  and  necessity ;  this  becomes  possible 

D 


50  §  5.  SYLLABUS  OF  THE  SYSTEM. 

only  by  connecting  it  with  tlie  Christian  idea  of  God.  To  be 
sure,  a  man  with  a  Christian  moral  sense  has  a  feeling  of  the 
truth  of  Christian  morality ;  he  has  an  immediate  inward 
certainty  of  it ;  still,  this  is  not  objective  scientific  certainty, 
but  rests  rather  only  on  subjective  feeling, 

2.  Necessity  of  connecting  the  ethical  system  with  the 
Christian  idea  of  God.  If  it  be  recognised  as  the  aim  of 
the  moralist  scientifically  to  apprehend  the  intrinsic  truth  and 
necessity  of  the  ethical  principles  of  Christianity,  then  the 
ethical  system  must  be  appended  to  dogmatics,  or,  more  precisely, 
to  the  doctrine  of  God  and  His  revelations.  It  is  true,  faith 
involves  consciousness  of  the  world  and  of  self  no  less  than 
consciousness  of  God ;  and  hence  it  might  be  supposed  that 
ethical  and  dogmatical  truth  are  co-ordinate,  and  that  it  would 
be  equally  admissible  to  derive  the  dogmatical  from  the  ethical 
as  its  foundation.  But  God  is  beyond  doubt  the  supreme 
source  of  morality  in  general,  although  as  a  matter  of  fact 
the  moral  sense  may  apprehend  self  before  it  apprehends 
God.  The  moral  sense  would  even  be  insecure  and  without 
basis,  if  ethical  truth  had  its  ultimate  foundation  only  in  the 
fact  that  conscience,  especially  the  Christian  conscience,  feels 
something  to  be  true,  and  has  an  inward  immediate  conviction 
of  its  own  about  it.  Indispensable  as  this  individual  inward 
apprehension  of  morality  is,  as  a  way  or  means  to  objective 
moral  knowledge,  yet  this  purely  psychological  procedure 
would  plainly  not  be  suited  to  the  nature  of  the  subject.  For 
by  such  a  representation  our  conscience,  and  in  general  our 
moral  knowledge,  would  be  made  to  be  that  in  which  the  idea 
of  good  in  general,  as  well  as  that  of  Christian  good,  has  its 
ultimate  ground ;  whereas  the  order  must  rather  be  reversed. 
For  either  the  ethical  idea  has  no  objective  basis,  but  only  a 
subjective  one,  or  the  ethical  idea  is  objective,  as  every 
Christian  assumes  it  to  be ;  and  in  that  case  conscience,  even 
the  Christian  conscience,  rests  on  it.  But  ethical  knowledge 
not  grounded  in  objective  ethical  truth  would,  when  con- 
fronted, e.g.,  by  unbelief  or  materialism,  come  to  suspect  itself 
of  being  only  a  subjective  fancy,  even  though  shared  by  many. 

Those  who  would  stop  short  with  laying  a  merely  psycho- 
logical foundation  of  morality  neglect  the  scientific  duty  of 
inquiring  after  the  objective  reality  which  forms  the  principle 


ETHICS  RESTS  ON  THE  CHl'JSIIAN  IDEA  OF  GOD.  51 

of  moral  being  and  knowledge.  They  give  to  that  which  is 
not  the  imnciioium  cssendi,  but  only  the  subjective  princijjmm 
cognosccndi,  a  position  as  if  it  were  at  the  same  time  the 
ultimate  principle, — a  confounding  of  things  which  leads  to 
a  false  autonomy.  The  Christian's  subjective  moral  sense, 
joined  with  conscience,  forms  only  the  point  of  mediation 
which  the  ethical  idea  that  is  in  God  posits  for  itself  in  order 
to  give  subjective  certainty  of  itself,  viz.  of  the  objective  idea, 
as  objective.  The  very  nature  of  conscience  vouches  for  this. 
For  conscience  is  not  a  knowledge  of  a  free  positing  of  moral 
law  through  the  al;)Solute  autonomy  of  the  individual ;  but 
it  is  a  knowledge  that  one  is  bound  to  a  spiritual  power  not 
posited  by  us,  which,  even  without  our  knowledge  or  existence, 
would  have  right,  worth,  and  truth  in  itself.  Because  the 
moral  knowledge  in  the  conscience  raid  Christian  conscious- 
ness is  knowledge  of  something  objective,  and  knows  too  that 
this  something  is  objective,  it  is  not  merely  subjective  know- 
ledge, but  subjective  and  objective.  But  this  directs  us  to 
the  idea  of  God  as  the  source  of  ethics.  For  morality  in 
general  does  not  first  come  into  existence  through  thouiiht : 
but,  on  the  contrary,  it  is  recognised  by  reason  through  a 
necessity  which  is  antecedent  to  all  subjective  activity, — a 
necessity,  moreover,  which  we  have  not  made,  but  which  lays 
hold  of  us  so  soon  as  we  come  to  specifically  hnman  conscious- 
ness. Since  this  is  so,  we  must  go  back  to  the  cause  which 
created  this  being  of  ours,  constituted  and  acting  as  it  does ; 
which  cause  must  be  recognised  also  as  the  ultimate  cause 
of  our  moral  knowledge ;  that  is,  we  must  go  back  to  God. 
This  going  back  to  God  harmonizes  also  with  what  has  been 
previously  said  of  the  relation  between  dogmatics  and  ethics 
(§  1).  Proceeding  from  dogmatics,  ethics  branches  off  into  a 
department  by  itself.  Although,  therefore,  ethics  does  not 
have  to  furnish  its  own  doctrine  of  God,  it  must  yet  be  derived 
in  an  introductory  way  from  the  specifically-Christian  idea  of 
God,  which  is  disclosed  to  faith  by  means  of  the  world  of 
revelation,  and  is  brought  to  systematic  statement  in  dogmatics. 

3.  Synopsis.  This  starting-point  being  now  presupposed, 
the  ethical  system  is  to  be  divided  into  &.  fundamcntcd  and  a 
co7istructive  part. 

The   First   Part   has   to   do   with    the   world   of    the   first 


52  §  5.    SYLLABUS  OF  THE  SYSTEM.       SYNOPSIS. 

creation,  but  with  this  in  its  connection  with  the  idea  of 
God's  moral  aim  for  the  world,  as  disclosed  in  the  Christian 
revelation.  To  Christian  ethics  belongs  the  consideration  of 
the  first  creation,  because  this  is  regarded  by  Christianity  as 
the  work  of  the  same  agent,  the  Logos,  whose  personal 
appearance  is  Jesus  Christ.  In  it  the  Logos  has  His  pre- 
existence ;  it  was  arranged  from  the  beginning  with  reference 
to  the  moral  purpose  of  the  world ;  and  the  Logos  created  it 
with  a  view  to  tlie  second  creation  for  which  it  is  to  be  the 
basis.  This  fundamental  part  has  to  consider  the  totality  of 
the  things  presupposed  in  an  ethical  world,  that  is,  the  whole 
arrangement  of  the  world  made  with  reference  to  morality 
as  the  world's  goal.  It  has  to  consider  the  preparatory  stages 
of  perfect  morality  and  its  factors.     It  has  three  divisions. 

The  First  Division  treats  of  the  natural  'world,  of  man 
physically  and  mentally,  also  of  nature  around  him,  of  the 
order  of  the  world  as  created  by  God,  irrespective  of  the 
moral  process  itself  properly  so  called.     (Sphere  of  Eudtemony.) 

The  Second  Division  treats  of  the  order  of  the  world,  so  far 
as  through  it  there  is  made  possible  a  moral  process,  and 
therewith  through  human  agency  a  second  higher  creation  on 
the  basis  of  the  first.  The  world  bears  in  itself  an  ideal 
purpose,  and  is  therefore  endowed  with  conscience  and 
freedom.  This  ideal  purpose  is  the  law  for  the  action  of  the 
moral  forces.^ 

The  Third  Division  delineates  the  practical  end  aimed  at 
in  the  moral  process,  or  the  ideal  cosmos  towards  whose 
realization  the  world  is  advancing  by  means  of  the  moral 
process.  The  realization  of  this  end  is  made  possible,  in  spite 
of  sin,  by  the  God-man  who  forms  a  part  of  the  plan  of  the 
actual  world.^ 

1  [This  Division  treats,  therefore,  of  the  formal  conditions  of  the  ethical 
process  :  of  the  objective  law  of  God,  of  the  subjective  law  or  conscience,  and 
of  freedom. — Ed.] 

2  [This  Division  describes  the  law  in  its  contents :  first,  the  practical  goal 
itself,  as  it  is  fixed  in  God's  order  of  the  world ;  at  the  same  time,  however,  by 
means  of  that  goal  the  way  to  it  is  also  fixed.  Hence  this  division  considers, 
in  addition,  the  moral  stages  leading  to  the  goal ;  the  stage  of  law,  the  imper- 
fection of  this  stage,  both  apart  from  sin  and  on  the  assumption  of  its  reality ; 
and,  finally,  the  stage  of  love,  wliich,  without  the  God-man,  can  neither  be 
conceived  nor  realized,  and  which,  therefore,  before  Christianity,  was  only  an 
ideal,  a  requirement. — Ed.] 


ETHICS  A  COLLATERAL  DErARTMENT  OF  DOGMATICS.  53 

The  Second  Part  will  exhibit  the  Christian  moral  world  as 
an  organism,  with  its  various  members,  in  which  law,  virtue, 
the  highest  good,  have  become  united  and  blended,  and 
become  so  more  and  more.  The  starting-point  of  this  Part 
is  with  the  actual  God-man  Jesus  Christ,  who  in  His  true 
manhood  presents  the  law  in  living  form,  and  who  is  personal 
virtue,  and  who  for  this  very  reason  becomes  also  the  prime 
source  of  the  realization  of  the  end  for  which  the  world  was 
made,  that  is,  of  the  kingdom  of  God.  This  Part  next 
describes,  in  its  origin,  its  continuance,  and  its  activity,  the 
human  personality  restored  to  the  image  of  God.  Finally,  it 
treats  of  the  ethico-Christian  world  as  divided  into  the  several 
moral  communities  which,  taken  together,  constitute  the  king- 
dom of  God. 

4.  By  this  arrangement  we  obtain  ethics  as  a  collateral 
department  for  dogmatics,  and  thus  secure  for  ethics  a  firmer 
structure.  For,  following  the  dogmatic  starting-point,  i.e. 
Theology  strictly  so  called,  which  treats  of  God's  ethical 
nature,  we  obtain  an  ethical  Cosmology  and  Anthropology, 
Ponerology,  Christology,  and  an  ethical  doctrine  of  the  king- 
dom of  God  as  the  ultimate  ethical  goal  (ethical  Eschatology). 

The  end  for  which  God  created  the  world  is  not  an 
impotent  thought,  but  an  earnest  one,  incessantly  striving  to 
become  actual  in  the  world ;  for  which  reason  it  cannot  be 
thwarted  by  actual  sin,  which  is  to  be  treated  of  in  ethical 
ponerology.  Accordingly  it  is  to  be  shown  that,  conformably 
to  the  eternal  divine  idea  of  the  world,  i.e.  conformably  to 
God's  moral  purpose  for  the  world,  the  original  thought  of 
love  proceeding  from  divine  wisdom  is,  on  account  of  sin, 
accomplished  only  in  the  following  way :  The  divine-human 
power  which  belongs  to  the  divine  idea  of  humanity,  and 
which  has  appeared  in  Jesus  Christ,  evinces  itself  as  a 
restoring  and  atoning  power.  This  power  inheres  in  the  Son 
of  man,  who  is  Son  of  God,  and  is  applied  by  him  for  the 
benefit  of  our  race  ;  and  by  this  means  He  builds  up  His 
kingdom  in  the  individuals  who  are  appropriated  by  Him,  and 
who  appropriate  Him  to  themselves.  This  kingdom  we  are 
then  to  consider  according  to  its  divisions  in  detail,  showing 
how  it  is  no  longer  merely  a  Platonic  ideal,  an  imperative 
possibility  or  law,  but  a  real  power  in  the  present  time  in 


54  §  5,    SYLLABUS  OF  THE  SYSTEM.       SYXOPSIS. 

which  we  stand,  and  an  object  of  Christian  knowledge ; 
though  a  reservation  must  be  made  of  eschatology,  which 
views  the  idea  of  the  kingdom  as  needing  to  be  transformed 
into  reality  by  means  of  an  ethical  process. 

5.  The  classification  here  given  is  adapted  to  the  ethical 
material.  It  has  long  been  recognised  that  morality  can  exist 
in  three  forms,  and  is  not  fully  viewed  without  them  all, 
namely,  as  Law,  also  called  Duty,  as  Virtue,  and  as  the  highest 
Good,  of  course  as  the  highest  moral  Good  in  the  world.  For 
the  absolute  Good  is  of  course  God,  who,  far  from  being  a 
result,  is  rather  the  living  prerequisite  of  the  highest  Good  in 
the  world.  Now  in  the  given  classification  all  three  concep- 
tions find  their  due  place,  and  in  such  a  way  that  at  the  same 
time  it  is  made  evident  how  the  idea  of  Good  in  the  three  is 
systematically  and  completely  unfolded,  and  so,  how  these 
three  taken  together  contain  the  whole. 

First,  the  law  is  to  be  considered  in  itself,  namely,  as  the 
moral  ideal,  or  the  Ought-to-be,  for  which  the  world  exists, 
arranged  as  it  is.  Since  this  Ought  stands  opposed  to  a 
natural  condition  or  fact,  which  does  not  yet  correspond  to 
the  Ought,  or  even  contradicts  it,  therefore  through  the 
impulse  of  the  Ought,  which  has  to  do  with  the  will,  there 
is  brought  about  a  process  in  which  morality  comes  to  he. 
Every  Should-be  demands  an  Is ;  it  requires,  not  merely 
single  acts,  but  a  state  of  being  ;  and  hence  the  subjective  goal 
of  the  process  is  virtue.  But  the  things  which  in  the  process 
are  as  yet  separate  and  only  striving  to  become  one,  seek  to 
become,  and  do  become,  blended  in  the  highest  good;  and 
just  this  union  is  the  fact  of  morality.  Law  and  virtue,  from 
which  the  highest  good  in  its  different  aspects  is  framed,  are 
thus  treasured  up  in  the  highest  good.  For  the  forces  of  virtue 
are  themselves  a  part  of  the  highest  good,  which  maintains 
itself  only  through  continual  reproduction  from  those  forces, 
whose  vitality  promotes  and  maintains  all  forms  of  moral 
good.  Moreover,  in  virtue  the  law  is  realized.  Finally,  the 
ethical  institutions,  such  as  the  family,  the  State,  the  Church, 
not  only  have  the  quality  of  being  products  and  acts  of  virtue, 
but  they  are  also  powers  objectively  existent,  which  through 
their  t/^o?  help  to  produce  virtue  itself,  and  confirm  the  law. 

But  this  consummation  is  only  the  result  of  a  moral  process 


PART  FIEST  ANALYZED.  55 

or  of  a  growth ;  for  at  first  this  union  does  not  exist,  but  the 
objective  law  or  obligation,  and  the  actual  state  of  man  with 
his  world,  still  stand  apart  from  each  other.  A  divinely 
ordained  natural  state  of  the  world  and  of  man  exists,  to  be 
sure,  with  a  wealth  of  capacities  and  of  susceptibilities,  which 
constitute  integral  factors  of  the  idea  of  the  kingdom  of  God, 
and  without  Mhich  as  prerequisites  the  various  phases  of 
Christian  good  could  never  be  attained ;  but  in  their  natural 
unmodified  form  these  faculties  are  not  yet  the  highest  good, 
but  only  materials  for  it  which  are  to  be  elaborated. 

The  Fii'st  Part  considers,  therefore,  the  necessity  of  these 
factors,  and  defines,  on  the  one  hand,  what  by  nature  is,  and 
on  the  other,  what  ought  to  be, — these  two,  each  by  itself 
And  so  there  come  into  particular  consideration,  first,  man 
and  his  world  in  their  natural  state,  which  are  designed  to  be 
incorporated  into  the  highest  good  tlirough  an  ethical  process 
(Division  1) ;  and  next,  the  law,  as  to  its  form  (Division  2) 
and  its  contents,  i.e.  the  world's  moral  goal  (Division  3), 
What  ought  to  be  and  what  is,  law  and  nature,  however,, 
must  not  be  left  separate  from  each  other ;  their  union  is 
absolutely  required  by  the  law  and  by  the  human  constitution 
itself  So  by  means  of  the  law  comes  a  moral  process  or 
development,  of  which  likewise  the  Third  Division  of  the  First 
Part  has  to  speak.  The  process  can  indeed  be  disturbed  by 
evil,  but  has  therefore  nevertheless  as  its  fixed  goal  the  task 
of  uniting  the  obligatory  and  the  actual,  which  task  is  con- 
summated essentially  in  personal  virtue.^  The  notion  of  virtue 
is  the  middle  term  wdiich  unites  the  obligatory  and  the  actual ; 
which  helps  the  law,  that  hitherto  is  only  ideal  and  not 
real,  to  its  realization,  and  which  on  the  otlier  hand  lifts 
up  what  is  merely  natural,  and  gives  it  an  ethical  character 
or  ideality.  For  this  reason  also  the  true  highest  good,  as 
to  its  principle,  takes  its  starting  -  point  in  this  notion. 
Therefore  as  the  moral  sense  matures,  the  requirement  of  the 
law  more  and  more  concentrates  itself,  not  in  the  requirement 
of  definite  things  to  be  done  or  not  done, — of  works  or  pro- 

^  [Until  the  process  readies  the  Christian  stage,  it  does  not  get  beyond  the 
antithesis  of  requirement  and  fact,  and  accordingly  belongs  still  to  the  legal 
stage,  and  ends  with  a  requirement  which  finds  its  fulfilment  only  in  Chris- 
tianity.— Ed.] 


56  §  5.    SYLLABUS.       PART  SECOND  ANALYZED. 

ducts, — but  in  the  requirement  that  the  whole  man,  this  unit, 
be  virtuous ;  or,  more  strictly  speaking,  since  sin  has  entered 
in,  in  the  requirement  of  regeneration,  tliat  is,  of  the  union 
of  nature  and  law,  by  means  of  the  Divine  Spirit  or  Christian 
Grace. 

The  Second  Part,  embracing  the  realm  of  Christian  good,  is 
on  that  very  account  also  a  presentation  of  the  highest  good. 
It  is  proper  to  place  this  at  the  end,  since  it  is  the  highest 
good  only  as  being  a  moral  product,  which  presupposes  the 
morally  productive  povrer,  or  virtue,  the  ethical  SvvafMi<;  with 
the  virtuous  actions.  To  be  sure,  the  ethical  institutions, 
such  as  the  family,  the  State,  the  Church,  not  only  have  the 
property  of  being  products  of  virtue  and  of  virtuous  acts, 
but  they  also  help  to  produce  the  virtuous  force  itself,  and 
thus  help  to  maintain  the  Good.  Otherwise  looked  at,  the 
virtuous  forces  are  themselves  a  part  of  the  highest  good. 
Hence  it  appears  that  the  Second  Part  is  not  merely  the 
■doctrine  of  the  highest  good,  but,  as  the  doctrine  of  the 
kingdom  of  God,  is  also  the  doctrine  of  the  virtuous  forces  in 
individuals  and  in  communities.  When  the  stage  of  per- 
fection or  of  Christian  good  is  reached,  virtue  and  the  highest 
good  are  inwrought  into  each  other,  neither  exists  v/ithout 
the  other.  At  that  stage  the  law,  too,  has  to  be  noticed, 
namely,  as  something  in  process  of  fulfilment,  not  as  mere 
oUigation,  inasmuch  as  virtue  is  nothing  else  than  the  law 
itself  translated  into  personal  life,  taken  up  into  the  will  and 
the  being ;  virtue  is  a  transition  into  a  new  mode  of  existence 
which  is  required  by  the  objective  law  itself.  The  acts  of 
virtue  also  show  their  intimate  relation  to  the  law ;  for  they 
are,  and  are  termed,  acts  of  duty.  Thus  it  is  clear  that  at 
the  Christian  stage  these  three  fundamental  conceptions  are 
preserved,  but  they  are  blended  together,  the  moral  law  itself 
requiring  that  they  be  thus  blended. 

If  the  First  and  the  Second  main  Parts  are  taken  together 
it  is  at  the  same  time  evident  that  our  method  makes  possible 
a  genetic  presentation  of  the  moral  element  and  of  the  moral 
goal  in  the  world's  history,  and  does  not  stop  merely  with 
a  description  of  the  actual  moral  state. 

In  short,  the  First  Part  presents  morality  as  a  requirement 
not   yet   realized,   as   law.     In   order   to   this,   however,   not 


SUMMARY.  5  7 

merely  must  the  moral  ideal  be  presented,  but  also  the  way 
in  which  this  moral  ideal  is  to  be  realized,  especially  in  view 
of  the  entrance  of  sin  into  the  world.  Since  morality  is 
designed  to  be  realized,  it  must  also  be  shown  what  process 
morality  must  pass  through  in  order  to  be  realized.  This 
process  also  is  included  in  the  moral  requirement.  But  it  is 
peculiar  to  this  process  itself  that  the  idea  of  good  first  comes 
to  consciousness  in  the  form  of  a  requirement.  Therefore  we 
must  not  merely  set  forth  the  abstract  ideal  or  the  require- 
ment, but  at  the  same  time  must  show  how  morality  in  the 
form  of  requirement  sets  the  process  on  foot,  and  how  it 
finally  points  beyond  itself  to  something  more  than  a  require- 
ment. The  Second  Part,  on  the  other  hand,  presents  the 
requirement  as  realized  first  in  Christ,  He  being  the  perfectly 
actual  and  virtuous  personality  and  germinal  principle  of  the 
kingdom  of  God ;  and  it  depicts  next  Christian  personality 
and  ethical  communities. 


^.— STAETING-POINT  OF  ETHICS. 

§  6.    Connection  of  Morality  in  general  tvith  the  Idea  of  God. 

The  dogmatic  source  of  ethics,  by  means  of  which  the  concep- 
tion of  moral  good  in  general  is  scientifically  gained 
and  established,  is  the  idea  of  God  ethically  conceived. 
God  is  the  Good  whose  ultimate  reason  is  in  itself,  or 
the  aboriginally  good  Being. 

Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  i.  §  26,  pp.  305-323. 

1.  In  recurring,  as  we  do  in  our  thesis,  to  Christian  dog- 
matics, particularly  to  the  idea  of  God  and  His  acts,  we  are 
only  concerned,  out  of  the  many  attributes  of  God,  or  objective 
limitations  of  the  concept  of  God,  to  fix  upon  those  which 
pertain  to  the  scientific  grounding  of  morality.  Therefore 
especially  the  so-called  physical  and  logical  attributes  of  God 
fall  for  our  purpose  into  the  background.  Three  questions 
are  of  decisive  importance  with  reference  to  the  basis  of 
morality  in  general.  (1)  Is  the  idea  of  morality  a  necessary 
idea  ?  (2)  Does  an  absolute  reality  belong  to  it  ?  (3)  How 
are  the  ethical  features  in  the  concept  of  God  related  to  the 
other  so-called  divine  attributes  ? 

When  the  idea  of  morality  is  conceived,  there  is  involved 
in  it  the  conception  of  that  which  is  absolutely  worthy  and 
supreme  ;  for  while  things  without  number  come  to  our  know- 
ledge which  have  worth,  yet  in  comparison  with  morality  every- 
thing has  only  a  limited  or  subordinate  worth,  e.g.  life,  power, 
beauty,  fitness,  and  utility.  Even  knowledge  or  intelligence, 
though  indeed  a  good,  yet  is  not  superior  to  morality,  but 
likewise  must  take  towards  it  the  attitude  of  servant  or 
means.  But  certain  as  it  is  that  morality  as  such  is  really 
conceived  of  only  wlien  it  is  conceived  of  as  thus  eminently 
unique,  still  this  decides  nothing  as  to  the  question  whether 

58 


MOEALITY  A  NECESSAr^Y  IDEA.  59 

it  is  a  necessary  thought,  and  whether  the  object  thought  of 
is  a  reality.  We  ask,  therefore,  is  this  idea  of  moral  good  an 
absolute  necessity  in  rational  thought,  or  is  it  only  a  subjec- 
tive, accidental  fantasy  ?  Must  the  reason  as  such  conceive 
of  the  morally  good,  which,  when  conceived  of,  is  conceived  of 
as  that  which  is  strictly  the  highest,  the  absolutely  worthy  ? 
Certainly  it  is  possible  for  man  not  to  conceive  of  this  idea ;  it 
is  possible  for  him  not  to  think  at  all,  or  to  be  employed  with 
only  finite  notions.  But  in  either  case  the  reason  is  not  con- 
ducting itself  as  active  reason ;  on  the  contrary,  it  may  be 
shown  that  only  by  means  of  this  idea  is  reason  actual  reason ; 
for  without  it  there  would  exist  for  man  only  what  is  finite, 
physical,  or  natural.  But  in  this  case  he  himself  would  be 
only  a  finite  being ;  shut  up  to  the  mere  world  of  nature,  he 
would  be  perhaps  the  cleverest  among  animal  beings,  but  not 
rational.  Kant  correctly  discerned  that,  in  relation  to  the 
natural  world,  morality  is  supernatural,  a  miracle.  For  a 
miracle,  in  the  strict  dogmatic  sense,  is  constituted  by  every 
specifically  higher  stage,  as  distinguished  from  the  lower. 

It  might  now,  however,  be  objected :  Man  himself  also  is  a 
finite  being ;  hence  it  cannot  be  said  that  he  is  not  rational 
until  he  conceives  of  something  having  infinite  worth,  viz.  tliat 
which  is  ethically  good ;  rather,  the  pure  conception  of  this 
seems  to  be  something  transcending  even  the  powers  of  man. 
But  we  reply :  Man's  finiteness  consists  in  his  being  not  self- 
existent,  but  a  creature  of  God ;  by  no  means,  however,  in 
the  fact  that  the  infinite  is  inaccessible  to  him,  tliat  he 
is  excluded  from  it.  By  the  very  fact  that  he  can  be  the 
vehicle  of  the  infinite,  he  is  a  reasonable  being.  If  it  be 
asked  whence  the  idea  of  moral  good  comes  to  the  human 
mind,  the  answer  is  as  follows :  This  idea  cannot  have  a 
finite  origin  from  nature  ;  in  nature  is  only  finite  adaptation  of 
means  to  ends.  But  the  absolute  cannot  be  derived  from  the 
relative ;  that  would  be  a  reducing  of  the  ethical  to  the  physical, 
and  would  therefore  be  a  denial  of  its  characteristic  essence. 
Just  as  little  can  the  ethical  idea  (cf.  §  5.  2)  be  derived  from 
the  ontology  of  the  human  mind.  For,  again,  it  is  not  really 
conceived  of,  if  it  is  conceived  of  as  a  merely  subjective 
product,  as  only  a  subjective  notion.  The  ethical  is  only  then 
conceived  of  when  validity  and   worth,  independent  of  our 


60       §  6.    CONNECTION  OF  MOilALITY  WITH  THE  IDEA  OF  GOD. 

thought,  or  even  of  our  existence,  are  adjudged  to  the  idea 
of  it.  When  it  is  considered  that  the  idea  of  morality  can 
neither  originate  from  nature  below  us,  nor  be  a  mere  pro- 
duct of  reason  (since  rather  we  become  rational  beings  only 
throu'rh  participation  in  this  idea),  the  true  doctrine  must 
be  that  man  as  finite  cannot  make  himself  rational,  but  that 
when  something  infinite  takes  form  in  him,  primarily  in  his 
intelligence,  he  becomes  a  rational  being.  The  eternal  ethical 
idea  itself  lets  itself  down  into  the  animated  dust,  primarily 
into  the  consciousness ;  and  ethical  knowledge  has  in  this 
very  idea  its  origin.  Considered  historically,  indeed,  morality 
comes  to  us  only  through  the  medium  of  our  own  thought. 
Conscience,  however,  does  not  make  a  thing  good ;  but  that 
\vhich  is  good,  the  ethical  idea,  apprehended  by  thought, 
makes  our  knowledge  ethical  knowledge.  Having  this  ethical 
knowledge,  we  recognise  ourselves,  not  as  creative,  but  as 
bound  by  a  higher  power,  by  the  ethical  idea  positing  itself 
in  us,  and  thus  making  us  rational  beings.  On  the  ground 
of  this  fact,  the  idea  of  moral  good  is  necessary  for  the  self- 
developing  human  mind.  This  appears,  too,  especially  from 
the  fact  that  the  ethical  lies  at  the  root  of  all  knowledge,  so 
that  to  renounce  it  is  to  renounce  all  knowledge.  Thought 
results  in  knowledge  only  if  it  icills  to  become  knowledge,  i.e. 
strives  to  gain  wisdom  as  a  good  (this  being  what  the  very 
word  (})i\oao(pia  expresses),  and  has  confidence  that  it  can  be 
attained.  But  in  both  these  things  lies  an  ethical  conception : 
on  our  side,  the  love  of  truth ;  on  the  other  side,  the  assump- 
tion of  its  accessibleness,  communicableness,  its  wish,  as  it 
\vere,  to  be  known,  its  love  of  being  known  by  us.  Only  such 
thought  as  involves  that  love  and  this  confidence,  and  is 
therefore  ethical  thought,  can  become  knowledge  and  attain 
to  the  high  quality  of  wisdom.  Therefore  without  the  opera- 
tion of  the  ethical  element  there  is  no  knowledge  ;  this  element 
belongs  to  the  necessary  conditions  of  the  possibility  of  all 
knowledge,  that  is,  of  the  rational  character  of  man. 

But  if  now  thought,  in  order  to  correspond  to  its  rational 
object,  must  count  on  an  ethical  element  and  incorporate  it  as 
an  impelling  factor,  as  love  and  confidence,  into  the  cognitive 
process,  then  it  must  also  be  possible  to  conceive  and  to 
define    the   ethical   as   such.      If  this   is   done,   the   idea   of 


MORALITY  ESSENTIAL  TO  THE  DIVINE  BEING.  61 

morality  {vid.  above,  pp.  58,  59)  is  recognised  as  something  not 
merely  subjective,  or  derivable  from  nature  and  finiteuess ; 
as  something  not  indifferent,  which  can  come  or  go  without 
affecting  the  rationalness  of  the  mind ;  and  finally,  as  some- 
thing not  merely  valuable  along  with  other  things, — but  as  the 
good,  the  absolutely  valuable.  It  is  a  thought  which,  if  it  is 
once  conceived,  cannot  at  pleasure  be  forgotten  or  ignored, 
but  demands  to  be  thought  again  and  again, — to  work  on  per- 
ennially, in  order  to  communicate  itself  to  the  whole  mental 
life.  If  it  is  once  thought,  it  is  a  possession  which  can  never 
again  be  rationally  given  up,  but  which  is  summoned  to  be 
omnipresent  in  human  life  ;  it  is  a  factor  authorized  by  a  higher 
inner  necessity ;  and  to  ignore  it  or  want  to  forget  it  would 
be,  not  merely  imperfection  of  discernment,  but  culpable 
neglect.  Where  the  ethical  idea  asserts  itself,  there,  too,  is 
present  the  consciousness  of  the  duty  to  remain  heedful  to 
it ;  this  is  not  a  physical  or  a  logical  necessity,  but  a  sacred 
necessity  adapted  to  the  realm  of  freedom.  Thus  moral 
thought  can  be  renounced  only  at  the  price  of  renouncing 
true  rationalness,  yes,  all  knowledge.  The  ethical  idea,  as 
soon  as  it  has  appeared,  puts  its  preservation  or  reproduction 
into  the  care  of  a  peculiar  necessity  of  its  own — duty,  which 
is  necessity  addressed  to  freedom,  and  therefore  the  highest 
form  of  necessity. 

2.  Of  this  thought,  now,  we  say  that  it  is  also  to  be  made 
a  part  of  the  idea  of  the  necessary  and  absolute  spiritual 
Being,  or  of  God.  For  since  the  ethical  idea  vindicates  for 
the  absolutely  valuable  the  highest  place,  it  must  also  have 
a  necessary  place  in  the  divine  intelligence.  Nevertheless  there 
still  remains  the  question  whether  the  ethical  idea  must  be  con- 
ceived of  as  also  real  (in  itself  or  in  God), — ^just  as  necessarily 
existent  as  it  must  be  necessarily  conceived.  There  are  not 
wanting  those  who  recognise  the  idea  of  morality  as  merely 
necessary  to  thought,  but  not  as  also  necessary  in  reality  ;  who 
conceive  it  only  as  a  necessary  obligation,  as  a  law  or  regulation 
for  the  world.  In  support  of  their  view  that  morality  is  only  a 
necessary  ideal,  but  no  reality,  they  might  seek  to  argue  thus : 
It  is  a  contradiction  of  the  notion  of  the  ethical  that  it  should 
be  directly  connected  with  reality;  for  rather  it  becomes 
actual  only  by  means  of  the  will  after   it   has   been   appre- 


62       §  G.    CONNECTION  OF  MOKALITY  WITH  THE  IDEA  OF  GOD. 

hended  by  cognition  as  a  duty.  A  certain  existence,  to  be  sure, 
the  law  must  have,  at  least  in  thought  or  knowledge,  but  this 
implies  that  it  has  at  first  no  existence  in  the  will.  To  this, 
now,  is  to  be  answered  :  It  is  indeed  indisputable  that  morality 
may  also  take  on  the  Ibrm  of  obligation  which  is  not  yet 
realized.  With  men  it  must  at  first  he  duty ;  and  yet  even 
this  points  back  to  a  real  existence  of  morality, — not  merely  to 
an  existence  in  the  intellect  which  at  the  same  time  is  a  non- 
existence in  the  will,  but  to  an  existence  of  it  at  least  in  the 
cause  by  which  the  rational  moral  consciousness  is  produced. 
For  to  such  a  cause  out  of  itself  the  human  reason  points, 
reason  being  not  posited  by  itself,  but  given  to  itself  by  the 
absolute  cause.  But  that  we  must  actually  posit  the  real 
existence  of  morality  in  God,  and  this,  too,  not  merely  in  His 
knowledge,  but  also  in  His  will  and  being;  that  therefore 
morality  cannot  be  conceived  of  as  merely  an  ideal  without 
existence,  and  God  not  as  mere  universal  law,  is  shown  by  the 
following  considerations. 

Existence,  reality,  is  no  indifferent  matter  for  the  idea  of 
morality,  so  that  it  would  remain  what  it  is,  even  whether  it 
remains  eternally  deprived  of  existence  outside  of  the  intellect 
or  not ;  as,  say,  for  mathematical  truths,  e.g.  for  the  laws 
of  the  triangle  and  its  angles,  or  of  the  circle  and  its  radii,  it 
is  indifferent  whether  there  is  a  triangle  or  a  circle  in  reality. 
For  rather  the  characteristic  feature  of  the  idea  of  morality  is 
just  this,  that  it  has  essentially  a  tendency  to  existence,  to 
become  actual  in  existence  ;  and  the  meaning  of  absolute  obliga- 
tion is  just  this,  that  for  the  obligatory  thing  a  real  existence 
is  demanded.  The  good  is  the  thought  which  seeks  to  move 
the  will  and  sway  the  being.  Schleiermacher  justly  says, 
that,  if  we  thought  the  law  of  morality  would  remain  eternally 
an  unfulfilled  although  unconditional  requirement,  we  should 
have  to  doubt  its  intrinsic  right  to  make  an  unconditional 
requirement, — that  absolute  impotence  would  not  consist  with 
the  right  to  unconditional  validity.  But  if,  now,  it  lies  in  the 
thought  of  morality  in  general,  that  it  unconditionally  re- 
quires for  itself  existence  also ;  if  there  even  inlieres  in  it, 
as  that  which  is  absolutely  most  worthy,  the  right  to  rule 
over  all  reality, — then  the  ground  of  this  can  at  all  events 
not  lie  in  the  ethical  principle  itself,  in  case  it  has  no  reality 


MORALITY  NOT  AN  ARBITRARY  CREATION  OF  GOD.  63 

in  God.  If  it  is  in  the  divine  intelligence,  it  cannot  desire  to 
remain  confined  only  to  it.  But  there  can  also  be  no  hostile 
power  conceived  of,  whether  in  God  or  out  of  Him,  which  is 
able  to  debar  morality  from  the  existence  that  it  desires ;  for 
then  the  Divine  Being  would  no  longer  be  a  unity  in  itself, 
but  would  be  duplex. 

Since  the  divine  intelligence  must  include  in  itself  morality 
as  something  necessary,  and  positively  requiring  to  be  real, 
it  follows  that  the  doctrine  of  Duns  Scotus  also  is  unteuable, 
namely,  that  morality,  although  for  us  obligatory,  originates 
only  from  God's  free  absolute  power  {supremum  liberum  arhi- 
trium),  but  that  God's  own  essence  has  nothing  to  do  with  it. 
He  thinks  that  it  would  be  a  limitation  of  the  divine  freedom, 
if  God  cannot  command,  as  good,  what  He  will.  But  this 
would  be  making  power,  this  physical  attribute,  outrank  the 
ethical  attributes.  The  Scriptures  say  not  merely,  "  Be  ye 
holy,"  but  also,  "  for  I  am  holy  ; "  not  only  do  they  speak  of 
a  divinely-given  law  of  righteousness,  but  according  to  them 
God  also  Himself  loves  righteousness.  He  who  has  conceived 
the  thought  of  ethical  good,  e.r/.  of  love,  cannot  do  otherwise 
than  think  of  this  good  as  in  itself  good,  hence  also  good 
absolutely  for  every  one,  even  for  God.  The  view  of  Scotus 
would  lead  to  the  conclusion  that  there  is  nothing  good  in 
itself,  but  that  although  we  know  this,  yet  in  our  subjective 
way  of  viewing  things  we  look  upon  that  as  good  which  has 
been  commanded  us,  and  because  it  has  been  commanded  us. 
But  behind  such  an  appeal  to  the  divine  power  or  arbitrary 
will  lurked  ethical  scepticism.  God  could  at  any  moment 
without  a  contradiction  of  His  nature  call  even  evil  good  ;  His 
nature  would  be  indifierent  to  the  distinction  between  good 
and  evil.  Both  would  be  outside  of  His  sphere  and  would 
belong  only  to  that  of  the  world ;  His  own  nature  would  then 
be  mere  power,  and  while  there  would  be  a  semblance  of  exalt- 
ing the  notion  of  God  by  putting  Him  above  morality.  He  would 
be  merely  conceived  of  physically,  i.e.  as  below  morality.  More- 
over to  man  also,  for  whom  alone  there  would  be  any  morality, 
conscious  virtue  would  be  an  impossibility.  For  virtue  must 
choose  the  good,  because  it  is  good  and  not  the  opposite.  But 
if  there  is  nothing  in  itself  good,  then  also  the  good  cannot 
be  chosen  as  such,  or  because  it  is  good  and  not  the  opposite, 


64       §  6.    CONNECTION  OF  MORALITY  WITH  THE  IDEA  OF  GOD, 

but  only  because  it  has  been  in  fact  commanded,  of  which 
command  the  Church  has  information.  Thus  it  becomes 
manifest  how  Scotism,  which,  in  order  to  exalt  God's  authority, 
keeps  the  good  out  of  God's  nature,  condemns  man  to  a  merely 
legal  status,  in  contradiction  to  John  viii.  32,  xv.  15.  Unless 
the  ethical  is  to  become  subordinate  to  the  physical,  it  must 
claim  admission  into  the  very  essence  and  being  of  God. 

But  morality  has,  moreover,  not  a  merely  potential  existence 
in  God.^  For  then  cither  it  would  become  actual  only  through 
the  development  and  growth  of  the  divine  perfections,  e.g. 
Avisdom  and  love.  But  this  would  be  a  contradiction  in  God, 
because  the  eternal  actuality  of  those  'perfection's  ivliich  must 
he  'prcclieatcd  of  Him  wonUi  tc  wanting  to  Hvm ;  and  this 
would  be  inconsistent  with  His  absoluteness.  Also,  over  a 
God  thus  conceived  of,  morality  would  have  to  be  conceived 
of  as  a  law  or  rule  to  which  He  would  be  subject  and 
under  obligation  gradually  to  approximate.  Or,  God  would 
have  to  be  designated  as  the  moral  law ;  but  this  has  been 
above  already  refuted.  Since  the  good  is  of  absolute  worth 
and  tends  by  its  very  essence  to  existence,  then  if  God  M'ere 
not  in  His  whole  actual  being  absolutely  good,  as  ctcrncdhj  as 
He  exists,  only  the  impotence  of  His  will  could  be  to  blame 
for  His  being  deprived  of  absoluteness,  whether  a  restraining 
power,  dualistically  conceived,  be  outside  of  Him  or  within 
Him.  So  this  position  must  be  adhered  to  :  not  only  that 
God  knows  and  wills  the  morality  which  is  for  us,  but  that  it 
makes  a  part  of  His  very  essence  ;  and,  moreover,  that  morality 
belongs  to  God's  being  as  an  eternal  fact,  although  in  human 
morality  obligation  must  precede  the  real  perfection.  The 
ethical  principle  itself  requires  to  take  this  course  in  the 
temporal  world,  and  disclaims  having  immediate  perfect  reality 
in  order  to  the  existence  of  a  world  really  distinct  from  God, 
and  capable  of  a  moral  progress.  But  in  God  such  a  dis- 
claiming of  perfection  is  not  conceivable ;  there  is  no  moral 
growth  in  Him.  If  morality  is  at  first  not  perfect  as  a  fact 
in  the  world,  so  much  the  more  must  it  be  such  in  God.  The 
idea  of  morality  cannot  have  an  empirical  subjective  origin, 
but  points  back  to  an  origin  in   eternity.      In   God   morality 

i  As  Rohmer  thinks,  Gott  und  seine  Schopfung,  18fi7,  and  similarly  Eduard 
von  Hartmann. 


EELATION  OF  GOD'S  ETHICAL  TO  HIS  NOX-ETHICAL  ATTRIBUTES.   65 

Las  an  aboriginal  existence,  it  has  a  place  where  the  actual 
is  eternally  perfect ;  and  therefore  it  can  become  for  the  world 
obligation  or  law.  As  law,  moreover,  the  good  does  not  float 
and  flit  around  in  the  universe  without  a  vehicle  or  real 
substratum,  but  eternally  rooted  in  God  it  seeks  to  spread 
out  and  to  become  fruitful  in  the  world  also  by  means  of  a 
process  of  growth. 

3.  The  third  point  is  the  relation  of  the  ethical  nature  of 
God  to  the  other  distinctions  which  we  ascribe  to  Him.  These 
are  in  part  physical  or  metaphysical,  as  omnipresence,  eternity, 
life,  and  omnipotence ;  in  part  logical,  as  intelligence.  This 
question,  too,  is  important,  because  the  order  of  these  attributes 
in  God  mnst  be  archetypal  for  man  made  in  the  image  of  God, 
and  for  the  order  of  man's  faculties.  But  there  are  three 
possibilities  conceivable :  either  the  ethical  distinctions  in 
our  idea  of  God  are  subordinate  to  the  non-ethical,  or  all  the 
divine  attributes  are  co-ordinate  with  one  another,  or  finally, 
the  ethical  element  in  God  is  superior  in  rank  to  all  the  non- 
ethical  attributes,  and  at  the  same  time  is  to  be  regarded  as 
the  bond  of  union  for  all  the  divine  attributes. 

It  might  seem  to  tell  in  favour  of  the  priority  of  the  non- 
ethical  attributes,  that  if  God  did  not  have  first  of  all  absolute 
being,  life,  intelligence,  and  so  forth,  we  should  have  no 
vehicle  for  the  ethical  qualities,  and  that  without  this  pre- 
requisite an  ethical  God  would  be  out  of  the  question.  But 
it  is  quite  consistent  to  hold,  that  what  in  one  respect  must 
be  thought  of  as  a  prerequisite  of  morality,  is  yet  not  on  that 
account  the  source  or  principle  of  morality,  and  must  not  be 
conceived  as  higlier  than  it.  The  non-ethical  distinctions  in 
the  nature  of  God  are  related  to  the  ethical  as  means  to  an 
end ;  but  the  absolute  end  can  lie  only  in  morality,  because 
it  alone  is  of  absolute  worth.  The  ethical  principle  is  the 
ultimate  reason  for  the  fact  that  God  eternally  wills  Himself, 
or  is  the  ground  of  Himself,  in  all  His  attributes. 

It  is  probably  most  frequent  to  conceive  of  the  divine 
attributes  as  co-ordinate.  But  in  that  case  there  would 
remain  unlimited  room  for  an  arbitrary  order ;  conceived  of 
as  real  potencies,  the  attributes  would  be  atomistically  sepa- 
rated from  one  another.  Where  then  would  be  their  intrinsic 
connection  with  one  another  ?   where  the  unity  of  God  ?     There 

E 


66      §  6.  CONNECTION  OF  MOKALITY  WITH  THE  IDEA  OF  GOD. 

must  be  in  God  a  dominant  principle  which  embraces  them 
all,  and  brings  them  into  harmonious  relation  one  to  another, 
in  that  it  makes  them  all  relate  to  itself.  This  regulative 
principle  is  presented  in  morality,  which  alone  is  an  ultimate 
end,  and  hence  is  paramount  to  everything  else. 

The  only  supposition  remaining,  then,  is  that  all  the  other 
attributes  of  God  are  sichordinate  to  the  ethical.  By  the  fact 
that  the  ethical  principle,  or  the  divine  mind's  absolute  mode 
of  existence,  presupposes  them  and  uses  themx  as  means,  they 
themselves  are  also  in  their  way  necessary,  and  participate, 
at  least  mediately,  in  the  teleological  system ;  they  have  a 
secure  place  and  an  eternal  foundation  in  the  fact  that  the 
absolute  ultimate  end  desires  and  demands  them  eternally 
for  its  own  sake.  These  other  attributes  are  thus  also  in  a 
sense  necessary ;  but  ultimately  they  are  so  for  the  sake  of 
the  ethical  in  God,  who,  in  order  not  to  be  a  lifeless  ethical 
being,  but  to  have  eternal  possession  of  Himself  as  an  ethically 
living  God,  eternally  wills  them,  and  through  and  in  them 
all  eternally  asserts  Himself  as  ethical. 

Note. — Fruitful  results  of  the  foregoing  for  Christian  ethics. 
If  morality  is  that  which  is  good  in  itself,  and  not  made  good 
only  through  the  absolute  authority  of  God,  and  if,  moreover, 
man  is  made  for  morality,  then  he  is  also  made  for  that  which 
is  in  itself  good ;  and  the  same  good  which  is  in  God  is  such 
for  us  also,  although  it  has  only  in  God  aboriginal  existence  or 
aseity,  and  the  manifestation  of  this  morality  in  us,  who  are 
created  by  God,  is  other  than  in  God  Himself.  Furthermore, 
if  morality  occupies  this  predominant  position,  all  attempts  to 
regard  it  merely  as  a  product  or  blossom  of  nature  are  definitively 
excluded.  But  the  consequence  following  from  the  foregoing 
which  is  of  especial  importance  concerns  the  relation  of  the  divine 
omnipotence  to  human  freedom.  If  the  ethical  nature  of  God 
requires  a  free  world,  omnipotence  cannot  hinder  this ;  the 
meaning  of  omnipotence  is  not  that  it  does,  or  must  do,  every- 
thing without  exception  wliich  it  can  do ;  rather  omnipotence 
itself  is  subserviently  subject  to  the  ethical  nature  and  will  of 
God.  The  above-described  subordination  of  the  other  divine 
attributes  to  the  ethical,  is  already  taught  in  the  Old  Testament. 
While  the  heathen  stop  short  with  the  immortal  life  of  the  gods, 
with  their  power,  beauty,  or  intelligence,  as  their  highest  pre- 
dicate, according  to  Prov.  viii.  God's  power  is  subject  to  the 
divine  wisdom,  which,  however,  wills  good  ends — ends  which 
in  their  ultimate  reference  are  moral.      The  ethical  element 


SUPKEMA.CY  OF  MOEALITY  IN  GOD.  67 

itself  is  in  the  Old  Testament  as  yet  predominantly  conceived 
of  as  holiness,  and  the  power  of  God  as  the  arm  of  this  holiness 
or  righteousness  ;  and  since  man  is  conceived  of  as  the  image 
of  God  (Gen.  i.  26,  27),  in  God  is  given  also  the  prototype  for 
the  relative  rank  of  the  faculties  of  man.  That  the  good  which 
is  valid  for  man  is  likewise  the  good  which  is  valid  for  God, 
is  made,  still  more  than  in  the  Old  Testament,  prominent  in 
the  New  Testament,  where  the  person  of  Christ  in  a  holy  human 
life  completes  the  revelation,  and  reveals  the  inner  character 
of  God.  The  difference  remains  nevertheless,  that  God  alone 
has  absolute  and  also  ethical  self-existence ;  that  man  exists 
only  on  the  ground  of  being  created  by  God. 

4.  What  has  hitherto  been  said  gives  to  morality,  as  an 
independent  good,  towering  in  its  height  and  grandeur  above 
everything  else,  a  firm  position,  and  that  in  God  Himself.  It 
is  a  necessary  thought  of  reason  as  such ;  it  is  really  conceived 
only  when  conceived  as  also  existent,  and  as  existent  in  the 
divine  essence ;  yes,  in  this  essence  it  is  the  centre,  the  inmost 
lyrinciijle,  God  in  the  Godhead.  For  at  the  same  time  with  it 
the  personality  of  God  is  conceived  of,  since  in  an  impersonal 
being  morality  cannot  exist.  Thus  originally  the  good  is 
God ;  and  God  is  both  that  which  is  aboriginally  good  and 
He  vjho  is  aboriginally  good.  Now,  too,  it  may  be  said  that 
morality,  according  to  the  idea  of  it  as  realized  in  God,  is  not 
merely  one  reality  among  others,  but  the  power  above  all 
realities,  the  highest  measure  of  all  worths,  therefore  the 
reality  of  realities ;  it  is  that  which  is  intrinsically  fixed  and 
eternal,  of  immovable  permanence ;  and  in  this  sense  Fichte 
names  it  the  "  substantial."  How  much  power  and  reality, 
what  form,  things  other  than  itself  shall  have,  ultimately 
depends  solely  on  itself. 

JVote. — Against  the  proposition  that  God  in  Himself,  and  even 
irrespective  of  the  world,  is  the  ethical  being,  objection  is  made 
on  the  part  of  those  who  grant  indeed  that  God  is  to  be  con- 
ceived of  as  ethical,  but  only  in  relation  to  the  world.  Morality, 
they  say,  requires  that  something  else  be  existent;  for  love 
consists  in  an  impartation,  an  act ;  but  impartation  cannot  take 
place  without  a  world;  God  can  give  nothing  to  Himself;  but 
if  God  is  one  who  imparts  Himself  to  others,  then  He  is  not 
love  in  Himself,  but  only  in  relation  to  the  world.  So  Kothe, 
and  similarly  Schleiermacher.  This  question  can  be  fully 
answered  only  through  a  closer  consideration  of  the  nature  of 


68  §  7.  NATURE  OF  MORALITY  IN  GOD. 

morality  in  God  and  in  the  world  ;  here  only  the  following  need 
be  said  in  confirmation  of  our  proposition,  that  morality  belongs 
to  the  inmost  nature  of  God,  It  cannot  be  in  Him  mere 
accident  or  caprice,  that  He  wills  to  be  self-imparting  love ; 
but  loving  impartation  is  not  possible  without  a  loving  dis- 
position and  will,  which  makes  the  recipient  its  end  ;  hence  in 
God,  independently  of  other  existences,  there  is  already  a  loving 
dis2)osition.  To  be  sure,  actual  impartation  presupposes  another 
being,  but  actual  impartation  is  not  the  only  form  of  real 
morality.  Even  without  another  object  already  existent,  the 
inward  willingness  or  inclination  to  impart — in  short,  the  loving 
disposition — can  already  exist.  The  mere  gift  w^ould  not  be  at 
all  appreciated  as  love,  if  the  disposition  did  not  put  itself  into 
the  gift.  Morality,  therefore,  cannot  exist,  either  in  God  or  at 
all,  merely  in  the  form  of  acts ;  it  must  have,  before  all  else, 
the  form  of  the  personal  power  of  a  good  and  conscious  will, 
in  other  words,  the  form  of  a  real  existence. 

§  7.   The  Nature  of  Morality,  primarily  in  God. 
(Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  i.  §  24-27,  oU,  32.) 

The  essence  of  morality  in  God  consists  in  an  unchangeable, 
but  also  eternally-living,  union  of  a  righteous  will  and 
of  a  loving  will,  in  the  narrower  sense  of  love ;  in  other 
words,  of  divine  self-assertion  or  self-love,  and  of  a  self- 
imparting  and  participating  will.  The  two  together 
and  inseparably  one  constitute  holy  love.  God  is  per- 
sonal ;  He  is  not  merely  that  which  is  aboriginally  good 
and  the  absolutely  highest  Good,  but  also  the  aboriginally 
good  One,  who  eternally  wills  and  asserts  Himself  as 
.  the  One  that  He  is.  But  this  self-love,  as  holy  zeal 
for  His  majesty, — His  ethical  majesty  also, — and  for 
all  which  this  demands  in  Him  and  out  of  Him,  is  not 
selfish.  Eather,  God  in  loving  Himself,  the  aboriginal 
seat  of  goodness,  also  loves  goodness  in  general,  which 
by  its  own  nature  requires  to  have  universal  validity 
and  sway.  Since,  then,  God's  self-love  loves  the  good 
in  general  and  as  such,  and  not  merely  so  far  as  it 
remains  His  own  possession,  it  is  not  contrary,  but  corre- 
spondent, to  His  self-love,  that  He  is  also  the  love  Avhicli 


LOVE  THE  ESSENCE  OF  GOD'S  MORAL  NATURE.  69 

multiplies  the  life  of  love  and  propagates  the  good.  By- 
virtue  of  His  holy  love  He  is  the  absolute  personality, 
absolutely  ethical — the  power  and  the  will  to  be  Him- 
self while  in  others,  and  M'hilc  Himself  to  be  in  others 
through  participation  and  impartation. 

1.  In  indicating  the  nature  of  morality,  we  cannot  aim  at  a 
definition  which  would  derive  it  from  a  higher  generic  notion, 
for  there  is  no  such  higher  generic  notion  from  which  it  could 
be  derived.  Yet,  on  the  other  hand,  we  are  not  without  an 
intuition,  a  provisional  notion  of  it,  which  is  capable  of  descrip- 
tion. Only  the  ethical  God  is  truly  God,  and  thus  is  verified 
that  saying  of  the  Bible  (1  John  iv.  8),  o  de6<i  djaTrr],  which 
again  is  not  a  definition,  but  aims  to  express  merely  the 
highest  Christian  knowledge  of  God.  The  Scriptures  do  not 
say  that  God  is  the  absolute,  infinite  being,  omnipotence,  or 
wisdom,  but  that  He  has  in  Himself  power  to  have  being 
and  life  from  Himself;  He  has  wisdom,  but  He  is  love. 
Hence  love  has  self-existence,  power,  wisdom,  and  so  forth. 
But  if  it  be  further  asked,  what  is  love  ?  human  words  indeed 
will  not  suffice ;  they  seem  to  us  tame  and  bald  in  comparison 
with  that  which  we  have  in  the  ethical  intuition  of  love.^ 
Let  us  consider,  first,  the  main  attempts  to  express  its  nature. 
But,  before  doing  so,  let  us  listen  to  those  also  who  look  upon 
it  as  absolutely  incapable  of  being  mentally  conceived  and 
comprehended,  because  it  is,  as  Kant  thinks,  only  something 
affectional ;  or  something  poetical  indeed,  but  only  an  indistinct, 
though  emotional,  state,  to  which  the  fancy  has  access;  or  some- 
thing so  high  that  only  vague  feeling,  but  not  clear  thought, 
can  grasp  it.  If  Christian  ethics,  however,  must  find  its  life  in 
the  principle  of  love,  it  would  at  once  abandon  its  claim  to  be 
science,  by  assenting  to  one  of  these  judgments.  Chalybams 
justly  says :  Love  is  the  stone  which  the  builders  (especially 
the  philosophers)  have  rejected,  but  which  is  destined  to 
become  the  corner-stone,  since  logic  and  metaphysics  can  only 
be  perfected  by  means  of  the  science  of  final  causes. 

2.  There  are  especially  three  views  of  love,  which  we  will 
consider   before    coming    to   our    positive    statement.       It   is 

^  A  poet  (Wolfgang  Menzel)  says  of  it :   "Tlip  more  thou  seek'st  to  strip  the 
rose  of  leaves,  the  more  it  seems  ^Yith  leaves  to  iill  itself." 


70       §  7.  NATUEE  OF  MOEALITY  IN  GOD.   LOVE  AS 

conceived  of  as  amor  concujpiscentice,  complaccntice,  and  hene- 
vokntice. 

(a)  The  «mor  concwpiscentice  seeks  to  supply  some  deficiency 
corresponding  to  which  there  is  a  desire  for  the  lacking  good, 
and  seeks  by  supplying  it  to  gain  the  agreeable  feeling  of 
completeness.  But  if  another  person  is  employed  only  as 
a  means  of  enriching  or  supplementing  one's  self,  this  is 
possibly  only  a  mode  of  seeking  one's  own, — a  sort  of  selfish- 
ness ;  and  the  same  would  be  the  case  if  the  person  having 
the  desire  wished  to  be  not  a  receiver,  but  even  a  giver, 
provided  he  only  gave  in  order  to  rid  himself  of  an  oppres- 
sive superfluity.  For  then  also  the  other  person  would  be 
only  a  means,  whereas  the  end  would  be  for  the  giver  only 
he  himself.  Plato  in  his  Symposion  has  invented  a  beautiful 
myth  concerning  Eros :  He  makes  him  the  child  of  iropo'i 
(plenty)  and  of  irevla  (poverty).  But  if,  on  the  one  hand, 
7r6po<i  or  giving,  on  the  other,  irevLa  or  receiving,  were  only 
selfish,  then  from  the  double  selfishness,  however  contrasted  in 
its  manifestation,  there  would  not  as  yet  issue  love.  Where  a 
relation  of  love  is  to  be  brought  about,  an  abundance  on  the 
one  side,  a  deficiency  or  an  unsatisfied  suceptibility  on  the 
other,  may  be  necessary  as  irrcrcg_uisites.  But  the  prerequisite 
is  not  the  thing  itself;  love  is  something  which  exists  for  its 
own  sake,  and  only  uses  the  prerequisites  according  to  its 
own  nature.  What  is,  then,  the  love  itself,  which  must  have 
a  place  both  in  him  to  whom  the  wealth,  and  in  him  to  whom 
the  want  belongs  ?  It  is  at  any  rate  something  else  than  mere 
care  for  one's  own  interest,  whether  for  a  lower  or  for  a  higher 
interest.  So  long  as  it  is  a  matter  only  of  one's  own  interest, 
we  remain  confined  to  the  natural  realm,  in  which  self-love, 
the  being  centred  in  one's  self,  holds  sway,  and  makes  self 
its  end,  and  into  which  only  adumbrations  and  premonitions 
of  love  fall.  This  mistake  is  avoided  by  the  conceptions  of 
love  as  amor  comjjlacentioi  and  heoicvolentia;,  by  which  some- 
thing other  than  one's  own  self  is  treated  as  the  end  and 
aim,  and  of  which  the  first  relates  to  the  intelligence,  the 
second  to  the  will. 

(h)  Amor  complaccnticc.  Tlie  love  of  complacency,  whether 
aesthetic  or  intellectual  complacency,  gives  itself  up  to  an 
object  in  recognition  of  its  worth.      It  can  pass  over  into  the 


AMOR  COXCUriSCENTLEj  COMPLACENTI^,  BENEVOLENTL-E.   71 

concupiscential  love  which  would  possess  the  object,  or  also 
into  the  amor  hcncvolenticv ;  but  as  such,  the  amor  compla- 
centice  reposes  in  mere  contemplation  of  its  object,  and  simply 
appreciates  the  intrinsic  worth  of  the  object,  without  letting 
the  will,  in  the  form  of  desire,  participate.  Of  this  sort  is 
intellectual  love  as  it  appears  in  many  forms  of  mysticism,  and 
as  treated  by  Spinoza,  where  the  losing  of  one's  self  in  contem- 
plation and  in  self-surrender  to  God  is  put  as  the  highest  love. 
As  applied  to  God,  that  style  of  thought  would  belong  here 
which  accounts  for  the  origin  of  the  world  thus :  God, 
absorbed  in  the  image  of  the  world  as  it  stood  before  His 
mind,  lost  Himself  in  it  and  imparted  His  essence  to  it  in  a 
sort  of  falling  away  from  Himself,  or  an  e/co-racri?,  which  is 
described  as  superabounding  love.  But  such  loss  of  self  in 
self-surrender  could  not  be  called  real  love.  If  the  world 
which  originated  in  such  loss  of  self  should  also  on  its  side 
have  love  resembling  God's,  then  it  again  must  lose  itseK 
in  God,  and  so  on  both  sides  love  would  consist  only  in 
self-annihilation,  or  in  an  absorption  of  the  loving  one  by  the 
loved  object ;  and  this  would  involve  the  end,  or  self- 
destruction,  of  love.  But  that  would  just  as  little  be  love 
as  the  absorption  of  the  object  by  the  subject  deserves  the 
name  of  love. 

(f)  It  sounds  better,  therefore,  to  describe  amor  as  henevo- 
lentia.  Tor  well-wishing  expresses  the  inclination  of  the  one 
person  to  make  tlie  other  an  end,  in  order  to  cultivate  with  him 
an  active  operative  relation  of  love,  especially  in  impartation. 
This  is  not  merely  a  contemplative  giving  of  one's  self  to  the 
other,  but  a  practical  making  of  one's  self  a  means  for  the 
other, — a  voluntary  relation.  This  explains  why  it  has  become 
almost  customary  to  regard  the  essence  of  love  as  impartation, 
or  self-impartation.  So  Schleiermacher,  Eothe,  et  al.  Against 
this,  now,  Schoberlein  urges  that  love  is  to  be  conceived  of, 
not  merely  as  impartation,  but  likewise  also  as  participation 
in  joy  and  sorrow ;  that  it  is  not  described  till  both  togetlier 
are  included.  Certainly  in  each  there  is  an  essential  function 
of  love ;  in  participation,  however,  not  in  the  sense  that  parti- 
cipating love,  like  the  amor  concuinscentice,  is  concerned  with 
getting  possession  of  the  good  things  which  belong  to  the 
other  person,   and   with  sharing  with  him.      Loving  partici- 


72  §.7.  NATUKE  OF  MOKALITY  IN  GOD. 

pation,  on  the  contrary,  is,  strictly  speaking,  a  giving,  an 
imparting  of  one's  self  to  the  other  person  in  sympathy,  for 
the  sake,  as  it  were,  of  continuing  and  enlarging  his  per- 
sonality, which  is  treated  as  being  an  ultimate  end.  Loving 
participation  therefore  belongs  properly  to  imparting  love, 
and  both  are  included  in  the  seeking  of  fellowship,  in  self- 
disclosure  made  for  others,  and  in  devotion  to  them  as  an 
end. 

But  is  now  henevolentia,  as  communicative  love,  the  adequate 
description  of  love  itself?  Impartation  would  be  an  act  in 
which  another  being  would  have  to  be  already  presupposed  in 
order  that  there  may  be  love  ;  whereas  (see  above,  p.  67)  love 
as  an  inward  faculty  and  disposition  can  already  exist  quite 
irrespective  of  its  manifestation  towards  the  objects  of  the 
love.  Otherwise  God  could  not  out  of  His  eternal  love  call 
a  non-existing  world  into  existence.  The  description  of 
morality,  or  love,  as  mere  impartation,  would  furthermore  not 
secure  it  against  the  conception  of  an  unethical  loss  of  self. 
For  the  impartation  would  have  to  be  in  some  sort  self- 
impartation.  The  bare  impartation  of  gifts,  while  the  ego 
holds  itself  back,  would  not  amount  to  love.  If,  on  the 
other  hand,  the  divine  love  were  conceived  as  disclosing  itself, 
but  onhj  in  the  form  of  self-impartation,  that  would  bring  us 
back  to  the  notion  of  a  pantheistic  self-loss  of  God ;  God 
would  be,  so  to  speak,  selflessly  dissolving  goodness,  and  this 
again  would  be  unethical.  True  love,  therefore,  must  not  fail 
to  have  the  seriousness,  sternness,  and  inflexibility  of  self- 
assertion,  in  order  that  it  may  not  become  selfless  expansion 
or  profusion, — in  a  word,  become  of  a  physical  nature,  like 
the  elements,  fire,  light,  heat,  water,  air,  which  have  a  natural 
tendency  to  expansion.  This  sternness  and  seriousness,  how- 
ever, is  not  expressed  in  henevolentia  as  such.  Summarizing 
Ave  say,  therefore :  Self-impartation  and  participation,  by  their 
nature  closely  allied  to  one  another,  stand  on  the  one  side, 
the  side  of  self-disclosure  or  self-devotion ;  but  these  in  their 
one-sidedness,  or  of  themselves,  would  not  amount  to  real 
love.  Love  conceived  of  as  amor  conc^'pisccntue,  however,  has- 
the  opposite  defect,  in  that  it  serves  only  the  ego,  making 
itself  its  own  centre.  The  two  taken  together  will  help  tO' 
put  us  on  the  right  course. 


POSITIVE  STATEMENT  OF  TEE  NATURE  OF  MOLALITY.         73 

3.  Positive  statement  of  the  nature  of  moralitii. 

The  definitions  already  considered  are  directly  opposed  to 
one  another.  For,  according  to  the  first,  love  is  only  a  seek- 
ing of  one's  own,  a  making  one's  self  the  centre  and  end ; 
and  this  was  its  defect.  According  to  the  other  two,  love  is 
conceived  of  as  only  devotion  to  something  else,  either  in  an 
intellectual  or  a  practical  way,  this  something  else  being  the 
objective  good  or  end,  for  which  the  agent  is  only  the  means ; 
and  this  was  their  defect.  This  indicates  that,  in  order  rightly 
to  understand  the  nature  of  love,  these  two  elements  must 
be  united,  and  must  be  viewed  as  forming  together  a  solid 
unity  of  blended  opposites,  viz.  the  choice  of  self,  which  we 
may  call  self-love,  and  an  opening  out  to  others  in  participa- 
tion and  impartation.  Morality,  true  love,  is  not  something 
merely  single ;  there  is  in  it  a  union  of  opposites  which 
it  brings  into  co-operation  with  each  other.  It  is  a  thing  by 
itself,  a  unique  essence,  ens  sui  generis,  as  much  so  as  any 
other  distinct  species  of  existence.  But  it  unites  microcos- 
mically  in  itself  what  otherwise  appears  only  isolated,  or  in 
one-sided  preponderance, — existence  for  one's  self  and  exist- 
ence for  others.  In  nature,  in  the  case  of  the  single  material 
forms  or  bodies,  the  ruling  impulse  is  self-concentration, 
the  force  of  gravitation,  reference  to  self;  in  the  case  of 
other  things,  as  especially  light,  it  is  expansion, — an  existence, 
as  it  were,  for  others.  Xow  love  is  a  more  composite  thing, 
an  infinitely  higher  power.  It  does  not  consist  merely  in 
acts,  which  are  only  its  outward  manifestation ;  we  must  also 
at  the  same  time  fix  our  eye  upon  its  inward  power  and 
essential  activity ;  for  the  manner  of  love  is  to  reveal  the 
inmost  and  best,  to  make  it  transparent  and  accessible.  In 
morals  the  outward  manifestation  has  import  only  when  it 
points  back  to  an  inner  source  in  love.  Accordingly  we  shall 
indeed  have  to  consider  love  in  relation  to  its  immanent  law 
of  life,  and  to  the  essential  functions  whereby  it  is  what  it  is ; 
but  in  doing  this  we  must  not  resolve  love  merely  into  a 
kind  of  action,  and  deny  to  it  the  possession  of  an  inward 
reality,  a  state  of  being,  which,  as  a  living  disposition,  also 
reveals  itself  in  action.  This  is  the  mystery  and  the  marvel 
of  love,  that,  on  the  one  hand,  when  we  fix  it  by  itself,  as 
being  in  itself  an  inward  reality,  it  insists  on  revealing  itself; 


74  §  7.  NATURE  OF  MORALITY  IN  GOD. 

for  it  would  not  be  love  if  it  did  not  seek  to  show  itself. 
And  in  this  aspect  of  it  we  behold,  just  in  the  depths  of  its 
inwardness,  the  purest  propensity  to  the  apparent  opposite, 
to  the  most  energetic  outward  manifestation.  But,  on  the 
other  hand,  just  this  full  revelation,  into  which,  as  it  were, 
it  has  put  itself,  and  in  which  it  has  come  forth  from  its 
inwardness,  points  most  surely  back  into  its  unfathomable 
depth  that,  even  in  self-manifestation,  remains  unexhausted, 
not  losing,  but  asserting  itself.  Just  by  means  of  its  intense 
outward  expression  we  are  most  surely  guided  back  into  its 
inner  depth,  its  pure  free  essence.  Thus  we  have  present  at 
the  same  time  both  its  distinctly  marked  manifestation  in  its 
single  acts,  and  its  fulness  and  depth  neither  circumscribed 
nor  exhausted  by  these  single  manifestations.  Both,  however, 
are  held  together  by  love,  which  is  the  true  bridge,  tlie  living 
bond,  between  the  ideal  and  the  real,  between  the  eternal  and 
the  historical.  There  is  no  power  outside  of  love  which  can 
imitate  it  in  this.  Of  the  forces  of  nature  it  may  be  said  that 
they  lose  themselves  in  their  manifestation ;  they  have  no 
inward  being,  no  depth,  even  though  they  may  have  secrets 
still  unknown;  they  exhaust  themselves  in  their  activity. 
Mind,  on  the  other  hand,  as  only  a  thinking  and  feeling  power, 
has  merely  an  existence  in  itself ;  though,  as  will,  it  has  at  other 
times  only  a  striving  to  get  out  of  itself  in  the  direction  of 
action  or  deed.  In  love  alone  is  the  real  and  most  thorough 
blending  of  these  opposites  ;  in  a  word,  it  is  the  "power  of  heing, 
at  the  same  time,  within  one's  self  and  out  of  ones  self  in  another  ; 
it  unites,  as  it  were,  transcendence,  or  self-assertion,  and  imma- 
nence in  the  world,  or  self-surrender  and  impartation ;  and  by 
the  union  of  these  two  it  becomes  holy  love.  The  pan- 
theistic and  the  deistic  conceptions  of  God  are  thus  left 
behind.  For  in  God  self  -  assertion  and  self  -  devotion  are 
absolutely  united,  but  are  not  therefore  identical,  as  we  shall 
presently  see. 

4.  Distinction  letween  self-assertion  {or  self-love)  and  self- 
impartation,  with  the  inward  conjunction  of  the  two  in  holy 
love ;  or  the  distinction  and  the  connection  between  righteousness 
and  love  in  its  stricter  sense. 

The  distinguishing  between  self-assertion  and  self-imparta- 
tion,  together  with  the  recognition  of  their  inner  connection, 


DISTINCTION"  BETWEEN  SELF-LOVE  AND  SELF-IMPAETATION.    75 

is  a  vital  point  in  order  to  an  understanding  of  the  full  con- 
ception of  holy  love ;  therefore  we  are  first  of  all  called  upon 
to  maintain  that  distinction  against  objections,  and  to  establish 
its  necessity. 

a.  Against  distinguishing  hetween  the  two  there  are  objections 
raised  from  respectable  sources.  These  are  directed  against 
the  propriety  of  associating  the  notion  of  self-assertion  and  of 
self-love  with  that  of  self-impartation,  while  no  one  disputes 
the  rightfulness  of  making  love  involve  self-impartation.  It  is 
said  that  the  love  of  God  wills  continually  to  become  active,  but 
that  God  Himself  cannot  be  the  object  of  His  own  love ;  that 
love  is  only  conceivable  as  love  of  another ;  that  self-love  does 
not  at  all  deserve  the  name  of  love.  If  this  were  correct,  we 
could  speak  of  love  in  God  (as  indeed  is  so  frequently  the 
case)  only  as  self-imparting,  but  not  also  as  righteous,  love ; 
righteousness  would  be  no  objective  attribute  in  God,  but  at 
the  most  a  subjective  conception.  The  reasons  urged  against 
our  position,  that  righteousness  and  love  (in  the  narrower  sense) 
belong  essentially  together  in  the  true  conception  of  love,  yet 
without  therefore  being  identical,  are  reducible  to  the  suspicion 
that  self-love  must  be  something  selfish.  Hence  some  would 
have  only  the  ^oorld  regarded  as  the  object  of  the  love  of  God, 
i.e.  of  the  self-imparting  love,  which  is  all  that  they  regard  as 
tenable  ;  so  Eothe  and  Schleiermacher.  Others,  as  Sartorius, 
think  by  resorting  to  the  idea  of  the  Trinity  to  be  able  to 
avoid  the  notion  of  self-love.  But  if  the  divine  distinctions 
or  hypostases  belong  to  the  divine  Being  or  self,  and  do  not 
exist  each  for  itself  separately,  but  only  when  taken  together 
constitute  the  one  absolute  divine  Person,  then  the  love  of  the 
triune  hypostases  to  one  another  is  also  divine  self-love ;  and 
only  Tritheism,  which  regards  the  three  as  constituting  no 
imity,  could  regard  the  love  of  the  Father  to  the  Son,  for 
instance,  as  not  being  self-love.  As  to  the  world,  however,  it 
cannot  be  the  primary  object  of  God's  love.  It  can  be 
worthy  of  love  only  as  destined  for  love,  or  because  love  is 
worthy  of  love.  But  why  now  should  love  be  worthy  of  love 
in  the  world  indeed,  but  not  also  in  God,  while  yet  it  can  be 
worthy  of  love  only  through  its  prototype,  the  God  worthy  of 
love,  and  through  love  to  Him  ?  If  God  is  worthy  of  love  in 
Himself,  He  is   also  worthy  of  love  for  Himself,  and  thus  in 


76  §  7.  NATURE  OF  MORALITY  IN  GOD. 

His  self-love  there  is  nothing  to  be  seen  except  the  righteous- 
ness of  His  love.^  The  a'pi^carancc  of  selfishness,  which 
Sartorius  finds  in  divine  self-love,  would  be  more  than  a  mere 
appearance  only  in  case  God  in  loving  Himself  thereby  loved 
merely  a  particular  being.  But  as  God  is  distinguished 
personally  and  from  everything  possible  and  actual  by  His 
self-existence,  which  is,  however,  at  the  same  time  the  ground 
of  universal  possibility  and  existence,  He  is  also  the  aboriginal 
and  necessary  seat  of  good  in  general — of  the  KaOoXov  a'yadov. 
With  the  eternal  universal  idea  of  good  of  which,  as  of 
all  eternal  truths,  He  is  the  aboriginal  seat.  His  absolute 
personality  has  consciously  and  voluntarily,  eternally  and 
indissolubly,  joined  itself  Hence  if  God  loves  Himself,  He 
loves  not  merely  an  individual  personality,  but  His  own 
unique  personality,  with  all  its  potencies  and  attributes,  all, 
however,  as  above  described,  in  harmony  with  the  dominant 
principle  in  Him,  the  ethical,  and  for  the  sake  of  that.  He  is 
thus  in  self-love  not  merely  love  to  His  own  self,  irrespective 
of  the  ethical  principle,  but  He  is  at  the  same  time  amor 
amoris ;  He  loves  the  ethical  principle  in  general,  both 
righteousness  and  communicative  love.  And  thus  selfishness 
in  the  divine  self-love  is  out  of  the  question,  because  in  loving 
Himself  He  also  loves  and  wills  what  is  universal,  wdiat  is  in 
itself  and  necessarily  good.  This  of  course  is  original  in  Him, 
and  must  eternally  fall  within  the  circumference  of  His  being ; 
but  to  this  universal  ethical  principle  belongs  likewise 
necessarily  the  self-assertion  which  we  call  righteousness. 
Even  without  self-impartation,  God  is  love  to  the  goodness  or 
the  holiness,  which  He  Himself  is. 

If  righteousness  be  not  regarded  as  a  particular  aspect  af 
the  full  conception  of  love,  the  gravest  consequences  result. 

^  [The  argument  liere  may  perhaps  be  made  more  clear  by  a  little  expansion. 
God's  love,  Dr.  Dorner  argues,  cannot  consist  merely  in  a  going  out  of  Himself 
towards  another  distinct  object.  For  why  should  He  love  the  world,  except  as 
it  is  worthy  of  love  ?  And  what  is  worthy  of  love  except  that  which  can  exercise 
love?  The  world  can  be  the  object  of  divine  love  only  in  so  far  as  it  contains- 
personal  beings  capable  of  loving  God.  And  there  can  be  such  beings  only  as 
God  creates  them.  Their  capacity  to  love  is  the  product  of  His  capacity  to  love. 
He  is  the  prototype,  they  the  copy.  God,  therefore,  cannot  be  conceived  as 
loving  the  world  unless  He  recognises  His  own  capacity  to  love  as  worthy  of  love. 
Consequently  self-love  in  God  is  necessarily  involved  and  presupposed  in  love  to 
the  world.— Ti:.] 


SELF-LOVE  ESSENTIAL  TO  ETHICAL  SELF-IMPAETATION.       77 

This  is  the  case  if  righteousness,  even  as  retributive  or 
punitive,  be  regarded  only  as  one  form  of  love,  love  itself 
being  conceived  of  as  consisting  only  in  self-impartation  and 
self-devotion.  It  is  equally  the  case  if  the  divine  love  be 
more  consistently  regarded  as  a  force  productive  of  that  which 
is  good,  and  if  in  righteousness  nothing  else  is  seen  but  the 
consistency  and  persistency  of  this  love  which  aims  to  produce 
and  impart  good,  that  is,  to  realize  the  end  for  wdiich  the 
world  was  made.  The  consequence  of  denying  that  the 
divine  justice  is  a  particular  clement  of  God's  ethical  nature, 
would  be  the  destruction  even  of  ethical  self-impartation,  yes, 
of  the  ethical  principle  in  general.  If,  that  is  to  say,  God 
should  be  conceived  of  as  self  -  communicating  love,  but 
without  the  self-assertion  which  constitutes  righteousness, 
then  God  would  be  wanting  in  power  over  Himself,  and  so  in 
power  to  control  His  self-impartation  according  to  the  intrinsic 
susceptibility  or  worthiness  of  the  object.  But  in  that  case 
there  would  remain  in  Him  only  the  irresistible  impulse  to 
self-devotion  which  would  have  to  operate  in  a  physical  way ; 
and  this  would  no  longer  be  voluntary  love,  but  God  would  be 
pouring  Himself  out  into  the  world,  to  use  Philo's  figure,  like 
an  overfoaming  goblet,  till  He  had  lost  Himself  in  impartation 
or  self-impartation.  In  that  case,  further,  the  freedom  of  the 
creature,  the  distinction  between  good  and  evil,  in  the  world 
would  be  disregarded.  Consequently  such  profuse  goodness 
would  tend  to  obliterate  all  distinctions  of  worth.  We  should 
have  therefore  only  the  heathen  conception  of  goodness,  even 
though  this  conception  might  conceal  itself  under  the  Christian 
name  of  an  overflowing  abundance  of  self-forgetful  love.  The 
New  Testament  speaks,  indeed,  of  self-forgetful  love,  and 
requires  that  we  should  lose  life  in  order  to  gain  it  (Matt. 
X.  39  ;  Mark  viii.  35) ;  but  that  means  that  we  ought  to 
renounce,  not  our  personality,  but  only  the  making  of  our 
finite  selves  the  centre,  the  shutting  of  ourselves  up  against 
God  and  our  neighbour.  There  is,  therefore,  a  place  in  God 
for  conscious  ethical  reference  to  Himself,  or  for  self-love  ;  and 
God's  assertion  of  Himself  as  the  absolute  personal  Good,  this 
guarding  of  His  honour,  is  God's  immanent  righteousness. 
Even  the  Old  Testament  conceives  of  God's  righteousness  as 
His  self-assertion  and  the  protection  of  His  honour.      "Who- 


78  §  7.  XATUllE  OF  MORALITY  IN  GOD.       GOD  IS  LOVE 

ever  would  pass  over  justice,  and  emphasize  the  importance 
of  love,  imagining  this  to  be  the  'New  Testament  conception, 
unavoidably  falls  back  below  the  plane  of  the  Old  Testa- 
ment ;  there  remains  for  him  only  a  physical  goodness  of  a 
utilitarian  sort,  that  is,  a  heathen  counterfeit  of  love. 

/8,  The  foregoing  discussion  serves  to  prove  the  necessity  of 
conceiving  the  divine  self-assertion  or  righteousness  as  a  dis- 
tinct thing,  as  a  particular  objective  quality  of  the  divine 
nature.  Yet  definitely  as  this  has  been  shown,  it  may  seem 
difficult,  yes,  impossible,  to  maintcdn  this  separateness  and 
distimxitness  as  over  against  self-imyartation  in  the  oneness  of 
God's  ethical  nature.  It  might  seem  as  if  self-assertion  and 
self-impartation  would  have  to  become  one  again,  because 
each  must  include  the  other.  For  suppose  now  it  should  be 
asked,  As  what  does  God's  holy  love  assert  itself  ?  what  is 
the  object  of  its  self-assertion  ?  In  reply,  it  could  not  be  denied 
that  God  wills  and  asserts  Himself  even  as  self-imparting; 
and  vice,  versa,  God  wills  so  to  impart  Himself  as  to  impart 
also  the  power  of  self-assertion  which  is  in  Him  to  living 
beings,  although  in  most  diverse  measure.  But  the  divine 
will  of  self-impartation  has  nevertheless  its  limits  ;  for  not 
everything  in  God  is  communicable  ;  the  self-existence  which 
runs  through  all  the  forms  of  our  conception  of  God  belongs  to 
Him  alone ;  and  so  the  very  aifirmation  of  His  aseity  or  self- 
existence  is  a  kind  of  self-assertion  in  God  which  is  not  at 
the  same  time  self-impartation.  The  will  to  impart  Himself 
does  not,  in  God,  come  merely  from  His  self-assertion ;  self- 
impartation  has  in  God  a  living  source  of  its  own,  which  is, 
however,  protected  and  cherished  by  the  divine  self-assertion. 
God,  further,  in  willing  and  asserting  Himself,  wills  Himself 
not  merely  as  self-imparting.  His  self-assertion  is  the  main- 
tenance or  preservation  of  all  His  attributes,  but  of  these 
attributes  as  means  for  ethical  ends.  It  is  a  maintenance 
both  of  His  self-existence  and  of  His  glory  and  majesty — of 
all  eternal  truths,  but  also  of  righteousness,  of  Himself  in  the 
distinction  which,  to  thought  and  in  fact,  exists  between  Him 
and  the  non-self-existent  world,  tlie  creation.  It  is  a  guarding 
of  the  difference  between  Him  and  the  world,  even  while  He 
imparts  Himself  to  it,  and  wills  to  be  self-imparting.  Agree- 
ably   to  His    uniqueness,    God   is   not    merely   the    general. 


EVEN  IRKESPECTIVE  OF  AN  OUTWARD  MANIFESTATION  OF  IT.    79 

universal  being,  the  source  of  everything  possible  and  actual ; 
He  is,  by  virtue  of  His  self-existence,  also  a  particular  being, 
distinct  from  everything  possible  and  actual.  But  this.  His 
particularity,  does  not  make  Him  finite  ;  for  the  very  essence 
of  it  is  that  He,  and  He  alone,  is  the  absolute  source  of  all 
other  things  possible  and  actual.  According  to  this,  it  is 
quite  possible,  without  confounding  self-assertion,  or  righteous- 
ness, with  self-impartation,  to  conceive  of  both  together  as 
elements  of  God's  inner  essence,  so  that  God  wills  and  asserts 
Himself  even  in  self-impartation,  and  so  that,  in  asserting 
Himself,  He  tends  to  impart  Himself ;  only  the  self-imparta- 
tion must  not  be  so  indiscriminately  conceived  of  that  thereby 
His  self-assertion  is  impaired. 

7.  And  no  less  is  it  possible  to  conceive  of  God  as  holy 
love,  or  capacity  of  love,  even  irrespective  of  any  outward  mani- 
festation of  it.  As  the  capacity  of  holy  love,  God  is  the  actual 
aboriginal  love,  the  actual  Good  and  the  highest  Good.  He 
is  in  Himself  the  absolute  Good,  not  merely  in  that  He  is 
infinite  fulness  of  life  and  of  powers,  that  He  is  will, 
intelligence,  and  the  union  of  all  potencies  in  the  form  of  per- 
sonality, but  also  in  that  this  His  personality  has  eternally 
and  absolutely  grasped  the  ideal  Good  and,  as  it  were,  clothed 
and  identified  itself  with  it.  All  the  divine  powers  stand  in 
eternal  perfection  and  unity  by  the  very  fact  that  the  Good, 
or  the  love,  for  which  they  all  exist,  is  the  inner  law  of  life 
in  God,  His  conscious  and  chosen  condition  of  life.  By  virtue 
of  love  the  divine  life  is  perfect  symmetry  or  eurythmia — 
absolutely  worthful,  self-satisfied,  blessed  harmony,  and  eternal 
Sabbatic  repose.  God,  as  the  eternally  perfect,  actual,  aboriginal 
love,  is  the  blessed  God.  But  God's  blessedness  is,  even  irrespec- 
tive of  the  world,  not  to  be  thought  of  as  inactive  rest,  but  as 
living  reality  ;  not  as  mere  potency,  and  also  not  as  coming  to 
be,  but  as  perfect  reality,  having  command  over  itself,  and 
being  eternally  active ;  in  His  activity  He  is  evermore  the 
blessed  God.  The  first  activity  (actus  primus),  however,  is  not 
a  cosmical  working,  hut  inner  activity,  or  ethical  life.  For 
God,  in  so  far  as  He  is  goodness,  does  not  conceive  of  Himself 
merely  as  goodness  fixed  and  perfect  once  for  all ;  but  the  good 
which  He  is  He  is  conscious  of  being,  and  wills  consciously 
to  be.      He  is  not  merely  a  physical  good,  but  what  He  is 


80  §  7.  NATURE  OF  MORALITY  IN  GOD. 

He  is  eternally  through  His  will ;  He  affirms  and  asserts  the 
goodness,  the  holiness,  which  He  is,  and  the  inviolable 
symmetry  of  all  His  powers.  So  also  God  eternally  asserts 
His  love  both  as  a  ccqxicity  and  as  a  disposition.  This  self- 
assertion  is  the  immanent  righteousness  in  God,  which  must 
be  conceived  of  as  not  merely  our  subjective  notion,  but  as 
an  objective  existence.  But  the  loving  disposition,  the  hcnt 
to  self-impartation,  is  in  God  different  from  rigliteousness, 
although  not  separate  from  it.  This  bent,  too,  must  not  be 
indulged  at  the  expense  of  self-assertion  or  righteousness, 
otherwise  it  would  lose  its  ethical  character.  The  divine 
self-love  is  the  impregnable  basis  and  the  necessary  pre- 
requisite of  self-impartive  love.  The  divine  self-love,  too, 
wills  to  maintain  the  immutable  distinction  between  God  and 
every  possible  thing  outside  of  Him — His  infinite  majesty, 
rooted  in  His  self-existence,  which  is  not  communicable,  but 
is  a  well-spring  of  life,  of  communicable  good.  This  self-love 
wills  also  His  personality  eternally  distinguished  from  every- 
tliing  which  He  is  not.  The  self-assertion  guards  the  possi- 
bility of  self-inipartation,  hut  is  not  the  so2ircc  of  its  rccdity} 

5.  "We  have  seen,  then,  that  absolute  self-love  and  self- 
communicative  love,  like  two  opposite  poles,  reciprocally 
and  indissolubly  connected,  but  not  confounded  or  identified, 
together  constitute  absolute  morality  in  God.  This  being  so, 
we  have  now  more  particularly  to  consider  the  essential  self- 
manifestations  of  the  impersonated  good  which  God  is. 

First,  (a)  The  self -manifestation  of  the  divine  holy  self-love : 
the  assertion  of  His  intrinsic  honour,  "ii23,  ho^a,  holiness,  or 
ethical  goodness  absolutely  maintaining  itself  in  its  absolute 

^  [The  author's  meaning  is  to  this  effect  :  1.  There  must  be  self-love,  self- 
assertion  in  God.  2.  By  virtue  of  this  self-love  God  asserts  the  distinction 
between  Himself  and  all  other  things  possible,  and  at  the  .same  time  Avills  to  be 
the  source  of  impartive  love,  yet  so  that  He  maintains  this  distinction  in  love 
itself.  3.  Impartive  love,  which,  even  irrespective  of  the  world,  is  in  God  as 
a  loving  disposition,  is  not  derivable  from  self-love,  but  is  a  principle  of  its  own 
in  God.  But  it  is  also  not  without  an  clement  of  self-love  :  (a)  so  far  forth  as  God 
wills  Himself  as  a  loving  being,  wills  His  loving  disposition  ;  (i)  so  far  forth  as 
the  loving  disposition  does  not  fail  to  maintain  the  incommunicable  distinction 
between  Him  and  every  other  possible  thing.  Thus  in  the  inmost  being  of  God 
there  is  found  the  union  of  righteousness  and  love  as  the  capacity  or  disposition 
of  love,  as  also  in  the  actual  self-impartation  the  loving  disposition  is  the  vital 
■  matter.     See  below,  5  (/3).     Ci'.  Syst.  of  Christ.  Dtjct.  i.  p.  456.— Ed.] 


HISTOIIY  OF  THE  NOTION  OF  JUSTICE.  81 

right.^  This  is  especially  prominent  in  the  Old  Testament  as 
the  zeal  of  God,  3'es,  as  jealousy  for  His  honour,  Ex.  xix.  ; 
Isa.  xlii.  8. 

Before  we  treat  of  the  essential  functions  of  righteousness, 
it  is  in  place,  considering  the  difficulties  in  the  conception  of 
it,  to  premise  some  historical  observations.^  In  the  whole 
ante-Christian  world,  the  Hebrew  not  excepted,  justice  is  the 
leading  moral  conception ;  it  even  sometimes  embraces  all 
morality,  according  to  the  saying  of  Theognis  which  Aristotle 
quotes:  "  Verily  justice  embraces  the  perfect  circle  of  virtue." 
And  justice  occupies  a  similar  position  in  the  Old  Testament. 
Yet  it  is  easy  to  understand  that  the  ancients  directed  their 
attention  more  towards  the  manifestations  than  towards  the 
essence  of  righteousness.  Furthermore,  a  law  is  presupposed 
as  a  standard  of  what  is  to  be  regarded  as  just ;  and  this  law 
is  at  first  conceived  of  in  a  purely  empirical  and  positive  way. 
Eight  is  what  the  laws  of  the  commonwealth  regard  as  right 
(v6fio<i  rrj'i  TToXewi),  although  they,  as  is  known,  may  be  even 
Itad.  Through  the  Sophists  this  formal  definition  of  justice, 
adapting  itself  to  accidental  laws,  became  filled  with  immoral 
elements ;  for  according  to  them,  if  one  has  only  possessed 
himself  of  the  highest  power,  which  gives  the  laws,  he  can 
also  determine  what  shall  pass  for  just,  and  make  his  own 
advantage   become   the    supreme   law.       Then   might  —  this 


^  Cf.  on  this.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  §  2.3,  24. 

^  Cf.  Hildebrand,  Geschichte  cler  Bechts-  unci  StaatspliUosoplde,  vol.  i.  p. 
123  sqq.  Leopold  Schmidt,  GescMcMe  der  griechischen  Ethik,  1881.  Trende- 
lenburg, Ilistorische  Beitrii<je,  iii.  399  sqq.  AUihn,  Z>e  idea  just i  qualis  fuerit 
apud  Homerum  et  Hesiodum.  Ed.  Platner,  Ueher  die  Idee  der  GerecJdigkeit  hei 
SophoUes  und  Aeschylus,  1858.  Hirzel,  Ueher  den  Unterschied  der  aiKaiotrinn  nnd 
crappurCvt)  171  der  plafonisclieu  Repuhlih,  in  Hermes,  \o\,  viii.  1874.  Ogienski, 
Welches  ist  der  Sinn  des platonischen  rk  avrav  "rpamiv  ?  1845.  [On  Plato's  view 
of  justice,  see  also  W.  Sn\\\\?,\^De  jusiitia  in  Platone],  Breslau  1851.  Fechner, 
Ueher  den  Gerechtifjlcfitshegrtff  des  Aristoteles.  Prautl,  in  Bluntschli's  Staats- 
worterhuch,  i.  342.  Diestcl,  Idee  der  Gerechtigkeitimalten  Testament,  in  Jahrh. 
Jiir  deutsche  Theologie,  1860.  Heft  2.  HeiVujkeit  Gottes,  ibid.  1859,  Heft  1. 
Zimmermann,  Das  Bechtsprinzip  hei  Leibnitz.  Hartenstein,  Bechtsphilosophie 
des  Hugo  Grotlus,  in  Abhccndlungen  der  scichsischen  Gesellschaft  der  Wissen- 
schaften,  vol.  i.  1860.  Stahl,  Die  Philosojjhie  des  Bechts.  Hinrichs, 
Geschichte  der  Bechts-  tind  Staatspjrinzipien.  Trendelenburg,  Naturrecht  auf 
dem  Grunde  der  Ethik.  F.  Dalin,  Bechtsphllosophische  Studien.  Vernun/t  im 
Becht,  Grundlagen  der  Bechtsphilosophie.  Schuppe,  Grundziige  der  Ethik  und 
BechtsphHosophie.     Cf.  the  literature  on  p.  28  sqq. — Ed.] 

F 


82  §  7.  NATUEE  OF  MORALITY. 

physical   thing — would   be   the   source   of    right,  a   doctrine 
which  still  later  is  defended  also  by  Hobbes  and  by  Spinoza 
[and  with  reference  to  the  derivation  of  right  from  God,  by 
Duns  Scotus,  according  to  whom  also  right  can  have  only  a 
positive    character,   since    it  has    its    origin    merely   in   the 
arbitrary   power    of  God — Ed.].     Tliis    is    the  definition   of 
Thrasymachos  in  Plato's  licpnUic,  in  which  work  the  philo- 
soplier  makes  Socrates  investigate  the  notion  of  justice,  and 
not   stop  short   with   merely  formal   definitions,  because,  lie 
says,  there  is  something  that  is  good  in  itself,  accessible  to  the 
reason  of  the  cognitive  person  through  self-knowledge.      The 
definition  of  Simonides  is  also  rejected,  who   advocates  the 
suum    cuique.      For    here    the    question    remains :    What    is 
that    which    belongs    to    each  ?       The    sophist,    who    makes 
might  supreme,  could  also  talce  advantage  of  this  definition. 
Besides,   the    suum   cuique    could    also    be    interpreted :     To 
your    friend,    good ;    to    your    foe,    evil ;     even    though    the 
friend    be    bad,    and    the    foe     good.       The     description    of 
righteousness  as  truth  in  speech  and  faithfulness  in  requital 
is    evidently   too   narrow.     Worthy   of  mention    also  is  tlie 
definition  of  Pythagoras,  who  makes  the   essence  of  justice 
consist  in  the  fact  that  an  avrnre'TrovOo';  takes  place ;  in  this 
an  important  function  of  justice  is  pointed  out,  namely,  the 
retributive,  or    punitive.      The   thought   is :    for   a    suffering 
that  one  has  caused  a  counter  -  suffering  is   the  just  thing. 
Yet   Pythagoras    took    avTnreiTovOo'i  in   a   wider    sense   also ; 
in   the  case  of  benefits  the  avTiire'irovOo^,  or   justice,  is  the 
recompense  made  by  gratitude.      So  with  him  justice  is  the 
restoration   or   completion  of  harmony,    and   that  in   a  pro- 
ductive way.     For  beneficence  demands  gratitude ;  gratitude, 
again,  is  active,  works   well  -  doing  towards    the    benefactor ; 
and  so  there  is  formed,  as  it  were,  in  living  mathematical 
movement,    according    to    the    principle    of    a    proportionate 
reimbursment    of   one   good   deed    by  another,   a   circuit    of 
active    benevolence.       In    this   is   shown   the    connection   of 
righteousness  with  the  mathematical  basis  of  the  world ;  and 
it  seems  that  Pythagoras  applied  his  principle  also  to  the 
matter  of  traffic  or  exchange.      Ptight  is  represented  as  some- 
thing   elastic    which,    when    it    has    sustained    an    injury   or 
pressure,  puts   forth  a  counter  -  pressure   or  impulse.      If  an 


Plato's  notion  of  justice.  83 

injury  sustained  by  the  right  is  to  be  bahmced  by  means  of  a 
corresponding  compensation  made  by  tlie  violator,  this  leads 
to  the  jus  talionis ;  and  therein  is  shown  the  connection 
between  justice  and  mathematics. 

Plato  takes  especial  pains  thoroughly  to  confute  the  view 
of  Thrasymachos.  He  maintains  in  opposition  :  If  justice 
were  only  what  is  imposed  as  law  by  the  stronger,  what  is 
pleasant  or  proiitable  to  him,  then  there  would  be  nothing  at  all 
that  is  in  itself  just ;  right  would  not  be  right  in  and  of  itself, 
but  only  something  absolutely  indefinite  and  mutable.  Thrasy- 
machos having  made  use  of  the  comparison  that  the  sheep 
are  for  the  shepherd,  who  can  therefore  shear  and  slaughter 
them  at  will,  Socrates  replies  that  this  comparison  does  not 
fit  the  case,  and  does  not  answer  to  the  relation  of  the  govern- 
ing to  the  governed  ;  that  the  shepherd  as  such  protects,  but 
does  not  slaughter,  the  sheep  ;  that  every  art  exists  for  the 
benefit,  and  not  for  the  injury,  of  its  object.  He  further 
urges  that,  according  to  Thrasymachos,  the  right  of  the  strong 
would  be  wholly  different  from  that  of  the  weak  ;  that  for 
the  former  to  rule,  for  the  latter  to  suffer,  would  be  just ; 
whereas,  rather,  right  exists  just  as  much  for  the  weaker  as 
for  the  stronger,  and  makes  one  care  for  the  advantage  of  others, 
under  some  circumstances  even  at  the  cost  of  one's  own.  He 
says  that  the  thesis  of  Tlirasy machos  is  to  be  reversed  :  that 
justice  is  the  necessary  condition  of  power  and  strength, 
while  injustice  engenders  strife  and  works  dissolution.  And 
so  Plato  seeks  to  represent  justice  as  the  bond  of  the  world. 
To  the  State,  which  is  for  him  like  one  great  person  in  the 
well-ordered  membership  of  its  parts  and  in  their  harmonious 
co-operation,  justice  serves  as  the  universal  rhythm,  the  music, 
which  runs  through  the  whole  and  keeps  each  part  in  its 
time  and  measure. 

In  opposition  to  the  derivation  of  justice  from  might,  and 
also  in  opposition  to  the  vague  definition  that  it  represents 
the  suum  cuique,  Plato  contrived  to  come  to  a  definite  point 
by  saying  that  justice  is  harder  to  be  discerned  in  individual 
life  than  in  the  State,  but  must  be  one  and  the  same  in 
the  State  and  in  the  individual,  for  which  reason  he  would 
have  it  learned,  as  if  written  in  large  letters,  from  the  nature 
of  the    State   as   being   a   magnified    individual.     The    civil 


84  §  7.  NATUEE  OF  MOKALITY. 

community  is  brought  into  existence  by  means  of  division  of 
labour  on  the  ground  of  variety  of  capacities  or  virtues.  Three 
classes  are  requisite  thereto :  the  labourers  or  tradesmen,  the 
Avatchmen  or  M'arriors,  and  the  rulers  or  philosophers — the 
classes  to  which  belong  the  three  functions  of  nourishing, 
guarding,  and  governing.  Each  of  these  three  classes  has,  ia 
exercising  its  function,  a  particular  virtue  to  represent :  the. 
three  are  moderation,  bravery,  wisdom  ;  the  fourth  cardinal 
virtue,  justice,  is,  according  to  him,  not  the  virtue  of  a  particular 
class,  but  belongs  to  all.  It  is  the  virtue  whereby  each  filLs- 
his  post,  is  what  he  ought  to  be  in  his  place  in  the  whole, 
—  ra  aurov  TrpdrTeLV  in  opposition  to  7roXv7rpay/j,oveiv  or 
aXKorpLoirpajfiovecp.  It  consists,  therefore,  in  the  individual's 
living  and  acting  in  accordance  with  the  character  of  his  own 
circle,  but  in  the  spirit  of  the  whole  ;  it  is  for  him,  as  a  part 
of  this  whole,  the  subjective  principle  of  virtue,  which  there- 
fore becomes  the  bond  or  living  soul  for  all  the  members  of 
the  body  politic.  The  groundwork  for  this  picture  of  the. 
State,  however,  is  the  Platonic  psychology,  which  distinguishes, 
between  the  three  things,  the  corporeal  life,  the  6vfM6<i,  and 
the  vov<;,  and  by  means  of  this  distinction  makes  it  possible 
to  speak  also  of  a  justice  and  an  injustice  even  in  the  indivi- 
dual as  such ;  for  the  subjection  of  the  physical  to  the  vov^,. 
e.g.,  is  just ;  and  the  violation  of  the  vov<i  by  the  supremacy 
of  one  of  the  others  is  unjust. 

Aristotle,  on  the  other  hand,  understands  by  justice  only 
the  virtue  which  is  suited  to  the  commonwealth  and  to  its 
positive  laws  ;  in  his  view  the  just  is  the  vofxLfxov.  To  be 
sure,  the  laws  in  one  State  are  different  from  those  of  another  ; 
therefore  justice  does  not  agree  with  actual  morality  ;  only  in 
the  perfect  State  will  justice  and  morality  coincide.  By 
reason  of  his  empirical  starting-point  Aristotle  does  not  get 
so  far  as  to  investigate  what  is  just  in  itsdf,  but  only  so  far 
as  to  eliminate  from  the  given  material  mutually  contradictory 
things,  and  to  hold  fast  those  which  agree  together.  Tlato 
goes  beyond  him  in  this  respect  also,  that  he  connects  justice 
with  the  Godhead  ;  the  ALkt]  he  places  by  the  throne  of  Zeus, 
which  calls  to  mind  the  word  of  the  Psalmist :  "  Eighteousness 
and  judgment  are  the  foundation  of  Thy  throne  "  (Ps.  Ixxxix. 
14).     Finally,  it  is  peculiar  to  Aristotle  that,  in  the  Nico- 


AiaSTOTLE'S  NOTIOX  OF  JUSTICE.  85 

rnacliseaii  ethics,  lie  is  willing  to  speak  of  justice  only  in 
relation  to  others/  but  not  like  Plato  in  relation  to  one's  self ; 
he  quotes  the  saying  of  Bias  :  Justice  is  a  good  which  belongs 
to  others,  that  is,  it  points  out  the  rights  of  others  and  one's 
duty  toward  them.  And  it  is  to  the  same  effect  when  he  says, 
that  no  one  can  do  himself  an  injustice.  On  the  other  hand, 
Aristotle,  as  compared  with  Plato,  shows  some  advance  in  the 
-apprehension  of  justice  ;  first,  in  relation  to  its  classification, 
and  secondly,  especially  in  relation  to  the  laov.  He  dis- 
tinguishes justice  as  BLopdo)TtK7]  and  as  ScavefxeriKyj.  The 
former  is  the  justice  of  equali/;ation  or  restoration,  and  includes 
the  justitia  commutativa,  or  the  justice  of  trade,  where  for  the 
•surrender  of  property  the  indemnification  lies  in  a  correspond- 
ing increase  of  property  by  what  is  received  from  the  other 
person.  Here  the  moral  character  of  the  person  is  indifferent. 
But  to  this  SiopdcoTLKij  belongs,  according  to  him,  punitive 
justice  also.  The  ZiavefieTLKi'}  is  the  j'list it ia  distrihutiva.  In 
the  State  inheres  the  right  of  distributing  property.  The 
■question  arises  now  whether,  in  order  to  be  just,  tlie  distribu- 
tion is  to  take  place  according  to  the  principle  of  the  laov, 
which  Plato  stops  short  with.  Aristotle  denies  this.  First, 
because,  according  to  him,  the  State  has  to  recognise  such  a 
distribution  of  things  as  has  become  historical  by  the  nature 
of  the  case,  or  by  custom  ;  and  secondly,  because  also  in  rela- 
tion to  the  things  which  the  State  disposes  of,  as  honours  and 
offices,  the  principle  of  the  tcrov  is  insufficient,  since  according 
to  it  all  would  have  equal  claim.  He  censures  Plato  for 
stopping  short  with  the  notion  of  the  laov  as  constituting 
distributive  justice,  according  to  which  there  would  result  an 
abstract  equality  of  all  men  (to  taov  caique), — which  would 
lead  to  democracy  or  ochlocracy.  The  'laov,  he  says,  is  only 
the  opposite  of  wanting  to  have  too  much  and  to  endure  too 
little,  and  so  denotes  only  the  supreme  rule,  that  every  one 
anust  receive  his  own  according  to  justice  ;  and  consequently 
there  remains  room  for  great  differences.  If  all  persons, 
A,  B,  C,  were  related  alike  to  all  things  good  and  bad,  a,  /3,  7, 
then  democracy  would  be  the  result,  and  every  human  being 
would  have  to  claim  the  same  as  every  other.  But  this  mere 
mathematical  equalization  is  to  be  rejected,  because  it  dis- 
^  Otherwise  in  the  Magna  Moi-alia,  i.  cap.  33. 


86  §  7.  NATURE  OP  MORALITY. 

regards  the  difference  in  merit  in  A,  B,  C.  To  apply  simple 
equalizing  lets  the  ZUaLov  be  lost  in  the  'laov,  and  that 
would  be  a  sort  of  tyranny.  Eather,  instead  of  a  mere 
equalization  a  proportion  is  to  be  laid  down  :  By  so  much 
as  A  has  greater  moral  worth  than  B  and  C,  by  so  much 
must  he  have  also  a  greater  share  of  good  things  and  a 
smaller  share  of  evil.  On  the  other  hand,  Plato  excels  Aris- 
totle in  that  he  makes  it  a  vital  point  to  investigate  what  is 
just  in  itself,  depicting  the  just  man  stripped  of  all  power, 
honour,  and  wealth,  laden  with  disgrace  and  obloquy,  in  order 
to  portray  the  irresistible  impression  of  justice  in  itself  con- 
sidered. He  excels  him  also  in  that  he  connects  this  justice 
with  the  idea  of  God  ;  whereas  Aristotle  stops  short  with 
experience,  which  can  set  up  as  justice  very  different,  or  even 
opposite,  things,  according  to  the  customs  and  laws  of  different 
people. 

Nevertheless  Plato  too  has  confounded  the  juridical  and 
the  ethical,  and  identified  justice  and  goodness  ;  and  as  with 
Aristotle  logical  and  mathematical  conceptions  are  especially 
prominent  in  justice,  so  with  Plato  morality  is  not  yet  distin- 
guished from  knowledge.  He  holds  that  after  the  knowledge 
of  good,  after  the  apprehension  of  the  idea  of  it,  the 
doing  comes  of  itself.  At  the  same  time  also  justice  is  sub- 
stantially made  to  appear  in  the  form  of  beauty,  that  is,  it  is 
looked  at  from  an  aesthetic  point  of  view.  In  this  is  seen 
a  resemblance  between  him  and  Leibnitz  in  their  treatment 
of  the  subject  of  justice. 

Leibnitz  makes  justice  rest  on  a  logical  or  intellectual 
foundation.  According  to  him,  justice  is  the  wisdom  of  the 
governing  person  ;  and  that  is  just  which  is  wise,  but  that  is 
wise  which  is  salutary  for  the  whole.  What,  now,  is  salu- 
tary ?  If  it  be  said,  it  is  that  which  promotes  well-being, 
this  view  may  result  in  utilitarianism,  so  that  justice  again 
receives  its  standard  only  from  experience,  which  ought 
rather  to  be  regulated  by  justice.  It  is  no  wonder,  therefore, 
that  the  philosophy  of  Leibnitz  in  the  eighteenth  century 
became  the  forerunner  of  popular  philosophical  utilitarianism. 
He  attempted  to  classify  justice  according  to  degrees.  1.  The 
jus  stridum  prescribes  only :  neminem  Iccde,  in  order  that 
every  one  may  not  lay  claim  to  the  right  of  the  state   of 


LEIBNITZ  ON  THE  NOTION  OF  JUSTICE.  87 

nature  or  of  war.  On  this  first  and  lowest  stage  justice  in 
commercial  relations  lias  its  place  {justitia  conwiutativa)  ;  this, 
too,  is  strict  justice  ;  under  it  there  is  exchange  of  the  idem 
or  the  tantundem.  Justice  in  private  traffic  rests  on  an 
equalization,  according  to  the  principle  that  the  thing  bought 
is  of  as  much  value  as  the  price  paid,  and  vice  versa.  But 
in  this  kind  of  justice  the  moral  world  of  personal  beings 
does  not  yet  come  to  view ;  all  are  regarded  as  equal ; 
only  those  differences  come  to  view  which  flow  out  of 
the  question  of  right  in  the  transaction  itself.  2.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  justitia  distrihUiva  has  to  proceed 
on  the  principle  of  suum  cuique  ;  hence  it  does  not  stop 
short  with  simple  equalization,  but  advances  to  a  pro- 
portion according  to  the  formula :  As  A  is  related  to  B 
(moral  worth  to  lot  in  general),  so  in  concrcto  is  C  related 
to  D.  The  lot  of  Cains  is  to  the  lot  of  Titus  as  the 
worth  of  Gains  is  to  the  worth  of  Titus.  3.  The  third 
grade  of  justice,  according  to  Leibnitz,  is  that  of  the  divine 
jurisprudentia,  whicli  leads  over  into  theology.  The 
voluntas  suijerioris  is  to  be  reckoned  as  justice.  But  God 
is  by  nature  the  highest  Being  ;  hence  His  positive  laws  are 
to  be  held  as  of  force.  From  this  he  further  infers  that 
what  is  stipulated  by  compact  is  to  be  reckoned  as  justice, 
and  likewise  as  2^'i'Ctas.  His  mcthodas  nova  jurisprudentice  lays 
down,  as  the  three  grades  of  justice,  strictum  jus,  a:quitas,  and 
pietas,  or  juridical,  political,  and  ethical  justitia  (the  last 
embracing  morals  and  religion).  He  would  let  theology  pass 
only  as  a  species  of  the  genus  jurisprudence,  as  treating  of 
the  equity  and  the  laws  of  the  republic  of  God — in  the  case 
of  ethical  theology,  of  the  divine  law  which  is  valid  in  private 
relations,  whereas  the  first  two  belong  to  the  realm  of  public 
justice,  but  remain  included  in  the  highest  of  the  three  grades. 
In  his  codex  juris  diplomaticus,  however,  he  makes  legal  and 
political  justice  also  find  their  ideal  in  God,  who  is  absolute 
justice.  There  he  describes  justice  as  the  leading  virtue  of 
the  affection  of  love,  or  of  the  benevolence  which  makes  our 
neighbour's  happiness  our  own.  In  this  way  justice  is  identi- 
fied witli  practical  wisdom.  The  proper  object  of  love, 
according  to  him,  is  the  beautiful — that  which  in  itself  it  is 
agreeable  to  contemplate  even  when  it  yields  no  advantage. 


88  §  7.  NATURE  OF  MOEALITY.       KANT,  HEGEL, 

It  is  true,  morality  and  beauty  have  this  in  common,  that 
both  are  pleasing  in  themselves  ;  but  this  would  bring  us  only 
to  the  realm  of  eesthetics  ;  nor  are  we  brought  beyond  it  by 
the  fact  that  lie  distinguishes  love  to  dead  works  of  art  from 
love  to  beauty  in  living  beings  which  are  capable  of  happi- 
ness, so  that  they  can  become  objects  of  benevolence.  The 
definition  of  love,  that  it  is  delight  in  the  happiness  of  others, 
or  that  it  makes  this  happiness  one's  own,  likewise  makes  the 
enjoyment  of  happiness,  i.e.  an  aesthetic  affection,  the  supreme 
thing  ;  and  ethics  thus  remains  the  science  of  eudremony, 
in  which  love  holds  the  position  of  means,  without  being 
recognised  as  something  good  in  itself — as  an  ultimate  end. 
But  justice  is  regarded  as  only  the  determination  to  main- 
tain a  wise  government,  not  as  the  choice  and  maintenance  of 
that  which  is  intrinsically  worthy. 

In  more  recent  times  Kant  has  manifested  a  particularly 
strong  sense  of  justice,  as  is  shown  especially  with  reference 
to  atonement  in  his  "  Eeligion  within  the  Limits  of  mere 
Eeason "  [and  no  less  in  his  theory  of  punishment :  The 
offender  ought  to  be  punished  "because  he  is  an  offender;" 
the  office  of  justice  is  the  protection  of  moral  freedom,  which 
in  itself  is  a  valuable  good. — Ed.].  Hegel,  too,  has  a  strict 
notion  of  justice,  which  shows  itself  particularly  in  his  defence 
of  the  so-called  absolute  theory  of  punishment  [and  though 
this  theory  is  grounded  ultimately  on  logical  necessity,  which 
is  the  central  point  with  Hegel,  yet  it  is  characteristic  that 
the  logical  necessity  leads  him  to  the  absolute  theory  of 
punishment. — Ed.].  Schleiermacher,  on  the  other  hand,  hardly 
finds  room  for  justice  as  distinct  from  love  ;  justice,  with  him, 
is  not  an  objective  attribute  in  God.  And  also  with  reference 
to  the  world,  to  which  he  denies  moral  freedom  and,  with  it, 
guilt  in  the  stricter  sense,  the  notion  of  punishment  is  for 
the  most  part  subjectively  applied,  and  thereby  weakened. 
Yet  he  posits  a  counection  between  collective  sin  and 
collective  evil,  a  connection  which  Pdtschl  wholly  denies, 
since  according  to  him  everything  which  might  be  regarded 
as  punitive  evil  is  rather  to  be  regarded  as  only  natural  evil 
Eitschl  does  not  recognise  objective  justice  as  a  divine  attri- 
bute. Justice,  in  his  view,  has  significance  only  in  relation 
to  the  State.      But  one  has  no  right  to  say  that  retributive 


SCHLEIERMACHEK,  EITSCHL,  ON  THE  NOTION  OF  JUSTICE.     89 

justice,  especially  punitive  justice,  has  value  for  the  State, 
but  can  have  no  application  to  God  and  His  action.  Eather, 
the  State  itself  does  not  have  the  right  and  the  duty  to 
administer  justice,  even  punitively,  except  as  right  is  itself  a 
divine  idea,  and  is  divinely  necessary.  It  is  both  logical 
and  just,  that  morality  be  not  powerless  and  weaponless, 
but  that  the  physical  creation,  which  as  to  its  very  origin 
occupies  the  position  of  a  means  for  moral  ends,  should  be 
subservient  to  morality.  Let  it  be  granted  that,  in  order  not 
to  vitiate  moral  motives,  it  is  requisite  in  rewarding  and 
punishing  to  use  only  with  caution  physical  means  for  pro- 
moting that  which  is  good  ;  still  the  idea  of  morality  does  not 
tolerate  that  the  malefactor  who  defies  it  should  not  have  to 
expect  a  punishment  corresponding  to  his  responsibility.  The 
denial  of  punishment  would  call  in  question,  with  the  imnish- 
ahlencss,  also  the  blameworthiness,  of  evil.  If  the  divine 
justice  did  not  lack  the  power,  yet  if  it  lacked  the  7'jill,  to 
punish  the  malefactor,  then  we  should  have  to  infer  indifference 
to  the  honour,  and  even  to  the  validity,  of  the  good.  It  is 
said,  indeed,  that  God  is  not  indifferent  to  good  and  evil ; 
that  although  because  prevented  by  His  love  He  does  not 
punish  sinners,  yet  God,  being  faithful  or  just  to  Himself,  will, 
as  a  logical  consequence,  overcome  evil  through  good.  The 
annihilation  of  sin,  it  is  said,  moreover,  answers  better  to  the 
idea  of  good  than  an  annihilation  of  the  sinner  does,  even 
though  it  be  only  a  partial  one.  So  might  one  speak,  and  so 
might  one  be  able  to  conceive  of  the  divine  agency,  if  there 
were  not  in  man  moral  freedom  of  choice,  which  can  oppose 
a  continual  resistance  to  the  production  of  positive  good 
and  to  the  annihilation  of  evil.  Also  God  cannot  treat 
alike  the  persons  who  are  good  and  those  who  are  bad. 
It  would  be  a  depreciation  and  disparagement  of  goodness, 
if  the  end  of  the  matter  were  that  the  world  of  reality 
could  belong  to  evil  just  as  well  and  safely  as  to  goodness. 

[Note. — The  conceptions  of  justice  mentioned  by  the  author 
are,  as  he  has  presented  the  subject  in  its  main  points  in  his 
lectures:  1.  "The  physical  view,  in  which  justice  appears  as 
an  outcome  of  power  (the  Sophists,  Hobbes,  Spinoza,  Duns 
Scotus)."  2.  The  one-sidedly  cesthetic  view,  which  appears  in 
Pythagoras  in  connection  with  mathematics,  and  is  in  some 


90  §  7.    NATURE  OF  MORALITY. 

measure,  too,  represented  by  Plato  and  Leibnitz.  Here  justice 
is  the  source  of  harmony,  and  serves  it  as  the  ultimate  end. 
3.  The  logical  or  intellectual  view,  found  to  some  extent  in 
Aristotle,  in  empirical  form  ;  also  in  Leibnitz,  to  whom  justice 
is  the  wisdom  of  the  ruler,  i.e.  the  means  for  the  end  to  be 
attained  by  wisdom,  viz.  happiness  (cf.  the  pnidentia  dei 
redoria  of  Hugo  Grotius) ;  and  in  Hegel,  who  makes  it  a  form 
of  the  revelation  of  the  immanent  logic  of  the  Absolute.  4.  The 
resolving  of  justice  into  love,  so  that  it  is  no  longer  something 
by  itself  (Schleiermacher),  or  is  made  the  logical  consequence  of 
love  (Ritschl).  5.  The  conception  of  justice  as  a  good  valuable 
in  itself,  found  to  some  extent  in  Plato ;  also  in  Kant,  and  not 
less  in  the  Old  Testament.  Here  justice  is  no  longer  merely 
good  for  the  sake  of  something  else — a  means  of  power,  or  of  har- 
mony, or  of  logic  or  wisdom — or  resolved  into  love.  But,  on  the 
other  hand,  a  connection  subsists  between  the  physical  world  and 
justice,  inasmuch  as  the  former  is  serviceable  to  the  manifesta- 
tion of  the  latter ;  justice  uses  power  as  its  means.  "  Justice 
has  also  relation  to  the  natural  'world,  so  far  as  everything  in 
it  is  conceived  of  according  to  rule  and  order,  and  that  which 
belongs  to  each  is  assigned  to  it.  This  thought  is  carried  out 
in  that  there  is  created  in  the  things  of  the  world  an  immanent 
order,  an  inherent  law  of  life  for  each  according  to  its  kind, 
from  which  they  cannot  wholly  break  away,  because  it  con- 
stitutes an  essential  part  of  their  existence,  and  which  man 
alone  becomes  conscious  of.  But  in  man  there  is  not  merely, 
as  in  the  natural  creation,  a  law  of  his  being  through  which  he 
continues  to  be  what  he  is.  Man  has  a  law  for  what  he  is  to 
become,  for  what  he  ought  to  be.  He  exists  for  a  history  and 
a  historical  goal,  and  in  this  even  nature  takes  part  through 
the  human  spirit.  In  man  there  is  a  law  for  his  freedom,  a 
moral  law  different  from  natural  law ;  and  this  moral  law 
especially  it  is  which  is  rightly  traced  back  to  the  justitia  dei 
legislativa.  In  his  dissertation  on  the  relation  of  natural  and 
moral  law,  Schleiermacher  says  indeed,  that  even  in  nature 
there  is  an  analogy  to  the  moral  law,  since  nature  produces  its 
formations  according  to  a  type  which  represents  a  sort  of 
obligation,  from  which  likewise  there  can  be,  as  in  the  moral 
realm,  a  falling  short.  But  to  none  of  the  occurrences  of  this 
sort  in  the  natural  world  shall  we  be  able  to  apply  a  moral 
judgment.  The  possibility  of  such  a  judgment  does  not  begin 
till  a  law  exists  which  by  its  nature  is  under  the  necessity  of 
making  absolute  claim  to  validity,  and  till  actions  are  presented 
that  are  to  be  judged  according  to  this  law.  Such  a  law  or 
olijective  right  has  its  unconditional  worth  and  its  claim  to 
validity  by  virtue  of  its  contents,  which  are,  in  general,  the 


THEOLOGICAL  CONCEPTION  OF  JUSTICE.  91 

good,  absolutely  worthy  in  itself  and  therefore  holy.  But  if 
righteousness  is  in  itself  worthy,  because  it  represents  the  self- 
assertion  of  the  good,  it  is  not  thereby  denied,  but  rather 
implied,  that  the  physical  world  should  receive  its  fitting  'plcice. 
Thus  righteousness  becomes  also  the  source  of  order  ;  and  it  is 
likewise  most  intimately  connected  witli  logic,  since  it  is 
logical  that  everything  should  be  determined  by  the  ultimate 
end."  Cf.  GlcmUnslehre,  i.  pp.  262,  263,  270,  283,  284.  In 
Eng.  Sys.  of  Christ.  Doct.  i.  pp.  276,  277,  283,  296,  297.— Ed.] 

In  Theology  justice  is  ordinarily  divided  into  justitia 
Icgislativa,  distrihutiva,  and  rcpcndcns.  The  foundation  is 
legislative  justice,  which  has  its  source  not  in  God's  mere 
omnipotence,  or  even  arbitrary  volition,  but  in  His  holy 
nature,  in  which  all  powers  are  eternally  willed  in  their 
mutual  distinction  and  order.  The  two  other  divisions  of 
justice  are  only  applications  of  legislative  justice  ;  the  justitia 
rcpcndcns  is  subdivided  into  the  vindicativct  and  the  remunera- 
tiva.  The  most  objections  are  raised  against  the  vindicativa. 
If,  however,  God  should  not  regard  evil  as  punishable,  but 
should  assume  towards  it  merely  a  reformatory  attitude,  the 
consec|uence,  even  if  it  were  not  a  total  obliteration  of  moral 
ideas,  would  be  to  make  the  distinction  between  good  and 
evil  a  matter  of  indifference — to  destroy  the  intrinsic  worth 
of  the  good. 

From  the  foregoing  follows  a  principle  of  great  ethical 
importance,  namely,  that  justice  is  the  indispensable  con- 
dition (conditio  sine  qua  non),  the  necessary  prerecj^uisite,  of 
the  reality  of  positive  morality  or  of  self-imparting  love ;  and 
in  general,  that  the  duties  of  right  precede  the  duties  of  love. 
The  reason  is,  righteousness  is  that  which  makes  possible  a 
self-impartation  that  is  ethically  normal  and  does  not  con- 
found moral  distinctions.  If  love  is  to  endure,  that  wdiich 
makes  it  possible  will  have  to  endure  also.  Nitzsch  rightly 
calls  righteousness  the  bulwark  of  holy  love ;  there  can 
consequently  be  no  love  without  righteousness  or  contrary  to 
it.  On  the  other  hand,  there  can  doubtless  be  an  exercise  of 
righteousness  without  loving  impartation.  These  two,  wliich 
in  the  ethical  nature  of  God  are  inseparably  joined,  in  the 
world  are  separated.  A  susceptibility  for  the  divine  imparta- 
tion of  love  may  be  wanting,  and  the  consequence  cannot  be 


'92    §  7.  NATUEE  OF  MOEALITY  IN  GOD.       LOVE  AS  SELF-DEVOTION 

loving  impartation,  but,  according  to  circumstances,  a  refusal 
of  it,  or  even  punishment.  A  loving  impartation  made  contrary 
to  righteousness  would  bring  everything  into  disorder,  might 
turn  the  moral  world  upside  down ;  the  supremacy  of 
righteousness,  therefore,  must  not  be  suspended ;  it  guards 
the  foundations  of  the  whole  moral  order  of  the  world. 

^.  We  come  now  to  consider  the  second  essential  manifesta- 
tion of  divine  love,  namely,  as  self-devoting  love.  We  have 
already  seen  {vid.  above,  Nos.  2,  3)  that  love  is  a  power  whose 
very  essence  it  is  to  will  to  reveal  itself.  But  its  self- 
manifestation  tends  to  take  the  form  of  impartation ;  pleasure 
and  delight  in  this  constitute  the  love ;  it  would  not  amount 
to  love,  however,  if  the  person  merely  bestowed  something 
else,  but  did  not  reveal  himself,  giving  himself  up  for  others. 
The  other  gifts  are  indeed  symbols  of  love ;  but  the  most 
precious  gift,  the  aroma,  as  it  were,  of  the  gift  of  love, 
is  the  loving  person  himself,  who  gives  himself  with  the  gift. 
l!^ot  every  act  of  giving  amounts  in  itself  to  the  bestowal  of 
love  (1  Cor.  xiii.  3) ;  it  is  such  only  when  the  bestowal  is 
attended  with  pleasure  in  bestowing  upon  another,  for  whom 
love  makes  itself  a  means,  or  whom  it  puts  as  its  end  and 
takes  into  itself,  in  order  to  have  companionship  with  him, 
and  in  order  to  offer  itself  to  him  for  the  expansion  of  his 
personality,  and  in  order  also  in  turn,  for  its  own  sake,  to  draw 
him  out.  Therefore  love  can  be  said  to  be  in  gifts  only 
when  love  already  precedes  the  giving ;  the  very  heart  of  the 
love  is  the  giving  of  the  heart.  This  self-forgetfulness  in 
devotion  to  the  loved  object  is  the  magic  of  love,  as  every  one 
knows  from  the  experience  of  family  love  and  of  friend- 
ship. In  that  it  devotes,  and,  if  needful,  sacrifices,  itself  in 
self-abandonment,  lies  its  wondrous,  conquering  power,  as  has 
been  shown  in  the  love  of  Christ.  Such  love  makes  the 
impression  of  having  original  divine  life,  of  being  a  power 
stronger  than  even  death ;  and  it  is  capable  of  transfiguring 
everything  about  it. 

Even  Greek  mythology  conceived  of  Eros  as  a  primeval 
power  and  as  a  hypostatic,  that  is,  substantial  being. 
This  self-subsistence  [Sdhststdndigkeit],  or,  to  borrow  Jacob 
Eohme's  phrase,  aboriginal  subsistence  [Urstiindiglceit],  of  the 
love   which    God   is,   cannot   be   destroyed   by  loving.      Eor 


§  8.    TRANSITION  TO  THE  WORLD.  93 

though  love  is  impartive,  yet,  as  above  shown,  it  asserts 
itself  even  in  loving  ;  the  self-forgetfulness  of  holy  love  forgets 
neither  righteousness  nor  love,  and  self-assertion  and  self- 
impartation  are  not  two  separate  acts,  although  distinguish- 
able. The  one  divine,  holy  love  consummates  in  inipartation 
the  act  of  self-assertion  also,  and,  so  far  as  in  it  lies,  even  in 
self-assertion  tends  towards  impartation.  In  short,  it  is  the 
characteristic  seal  and  privilege  of  love,  that  it  is  what  no 
other  force  besides  it  can  imitate — not  nature,  not  thought,  not 
will — namely,  the  power  and  the  desire  to  be  one's  self  while 
in  another,  and  wliile  one's  self  to  be  in  another,  who  is  taken, 
into  the  heart  as  an  end. 


§  8.   Transition  to  the  World  (cf.  Christian  Doctrine,  §  33). 

God,  as  being  holy  love,  wills  that  there  be,  distinct  from 
Himself,  a  world  designed  for  morality,  as  also  morality 
is  designed  for  it. 

1.  Our  thesis  makes  the  transition  to  ethical  cosmology  and 
anthropology.  Against  the  proposition  of  the  thesis  it  is 
maintained,  to  be  sure,  that  if  God  is  already  perfect  and 
blessed  in  Himself  without  the  world,  and  does  not  need  it  in 
order  to  the  perfection  of  His  being,  then  there  is  no  longer 
any  reason  for  the  origin  of  the  world.  For  if  perfection 
already  exists  without  the  world,  why  should  the  world  be 
added  as  a  bad  copy  or  imperfect  likeness  ?  Therefore,  it  is 
said,  the  world  is  to  be  arrived  at  only  by  assuming  a  defect 
in  God,  which  is  supplied  by  means  of  the  world,  wiiether 
this  defect  consist  in  a  superfluity  or  in  a  deficiency.  This 
error  of  pantheism,  that  there  is  a  deficiency  in  God  and  a 
growth  towards  perfection,  is,  from  our  point  of  view,  confuted 
by  saying  that  aboriginal  morality  is  to  be  conceived  of  as 
an  existent  reality,  ontologically,  not  as  mere  obligation ;  and 
God,  therefore,  not  as  a  process,  but  as  being  eternally 
perfect. 

2.  But  must  we  not  agree  now  with  those  who,  because 
God  is  to  be  conceived  of  as  self-sufficient  and  perfect,  regard 
the  world  as  purely  accidental,  and  deny  that  there  is  any 
rational  ground  to  be  given  for  its  origin  ?     This  opinion  loves 


94  §  8.    TEANSITION  TO  THE  WORLD.       GOD's  LOVE 

to  put  on  the  garb  of  appearing  to  defend  God's  honour  and 
majesty ;  the  world,  they  say,  proceeded  from  the  free  good- 
pleasure,  the  groundless  arhitrium,  of  God.  But  to  make 
such  a  groundless  good-pleasure  the  supreme  thing  in  God 
would  be  assuming  that  arbitrary  will,  i.e.  a  natural  attribute, 
mere  absolute  power,  is  the  highest  thing  in  God ;  but  this, 
ethically  considered,  stands  on  the  same  plane  again  as 
pantheism.  In  that  case,  too,  the  world  would  be  without 
worth  for  God  ;  it  would  not  have  been  made  by  God  as  a 
worthy  end,  but  would  occupy  only  the  position  of  a  means, 
serving  as  the  sport  of  His  caprice. 

3.  To  be  sure,  there  belongs  to  the  world  a  relative 
fortuitousness ;  first,  in  the  sense  that  the  reason  for  its  being 
lies  outside  of  itself ;  secondly,  because  it  is  not  necessary  to 
the  being  and  independence  of  the  perfect  God  that  there 
should  be  a  world.  But  it  is  not  absolutely  fortuitous,  for  if 
so,  it  would  have  also  in  God's  eyes  absolutely  no  worth 
(contrary  to  Gen.  i.  31) ;  and  it  would  have  to  be  for  us  also 
absolutely  fortuitous,  provided  we  have  the  true  apprehension 
of  the  case  ;  moreover,  we  should  have  to  treat  it  as  something 
indifferent,  worthless  in  itself,  i.e.  treat  it  unethically.  The 
correct  solution  lies  in  the  recognition  of  God  as  holy  love ; 
neither  from  a  physical  necessity  of  His  being,  nor  from  the 
mere  arbitrary  will  of  His  omnipotence,  is  the  world  to  be 
derived,  but  from  the  divine  freedom,  which  is  in  itself  ethical, 
and  is  a  true  divine  freedom,  by  virtue  of  the  fact  that  it  is 
united  with  that  which  is  ethically  necessary  or  good.  Thus 
also  it  becomes  possible  that  the  world  should  be  not  a  mere 
means,  devoid  of  selfhood,  attaining,  as  related  to  God,  only 
a  seeming  reality.  For  because  God  is  already  in  Himself 
perfect  and  blessed,  and  does  not  need  the  world  for  the  sake 
of  His  own  existence,  He  can  will  a  world  which  in  itself 
has  a  worthy  object.  But  in  His  love  He  is  perfect  and 
blessed.  The  love  is,  indeed,  primarily  directed  towards  Him- 
self, but  so  that  God  as  love,  or  because  He  is  love,  wills 
Himself.  By  virtue  of  His  self-love  He  necessarily  loves  love 
in  general ;  and,  wherever  it  is  found,  loves  Himself  as  the 
original  seat  of  the  absolute  amor  amoris. 

The  self-love  of  God  or  His  righteousness,  therefore,  since 
it  loves  love  as  such,  does  not  exclude  the  possibility  of  God's 


THE  SOUECE  OF  THE  CREATED  WORLD.  95 

creating  a  good  distinct  from  Himself.  On  the  contrary,  God 
cannot  love  Himself  without  also  loving  Himself  as  the 
possibility  of  something  else,  provided  this  can  exist  as  an 
object  of  love.  And  the  case  is  similar  respecting  God's  self- 
consciousness.  To  distinguish  His  self-consciousness  perfectly 
from  everything  which  He  is  not,  must  also  be  to  distinguish 
it  from  every  possible  thing  which  He  is  not;  it  therefore 
implies  something  else  as  possible.  To  be  sure,  we  have  so 
far  only  the  abstract  'possibility  of  another  being  besides  God. 
But  this  world  of  abstract  possibility,  at  the  impulse  of  love, 
and  through  God's  intelligence  or  wisdom,  which  is  love's 
master- workman  (Prov.  viii.  30),  becomes  the  image  of  the 
world,  the  idea  of  the  cosmos ;  and,  upon  the  same  impulse 
of  love,  omnipotence,  joined  with  wisdom,  calls  the  world  out 
of  non-existence,  or  mere  possibility,  into  existence. 

Furthermore,  the  divine  love,  in  accordance  with  its  singleness, 
makes  the  loved  object  a  worthy  end,  in  that  it  destines  the 
world  for  love,  and  thus  for  what  is  highest  and  perfect, 
although  this  can  be  attained  only  by  a  gradual  process,  inas- 
much as  God  alone  has  aseity.  But  by  virtue  of  this  moral 
destination  there  is  guaranteed  to  the  creature  a  relative 
independence,  a  vital  force,  and  a  causality  of  its  own.  God's 
self-impartation  does  not  overflow  the  creature,  as  it  were,  in 
an  unrestrained  giving  of  Himself  away ;  for  then  the  creature 
would  be  swallowed  up  and  would  not  come  to  a  being  of  its 
own.  Eather,  the  first  thing  is  that  to  the  creature  is  lent  a 
capacity  of  existing  by  itself  and  of  asserting  itself,  whereby  it 
becomes  a  relatively  independent  copy  of  the  divine  self- 
assertion.  Thus  the  world  becomes  for  God  Himself  a  new 
reality.  Only  by  virtue  of  the  distinction  between  God  and 
the  creature  in  its  living  independence  and  self-assertion  is 
there  given  the  possibility  of  a  real  interchange  of  love 
between  God  and  the  creature. 

On  the  basis  now  of  this  relative  independence  a  continued 
impartation  of  divine  love  is  also  possible,  so  that  not  only 
has  the  creature  a  moral  destination,  but  also  the  aboriginally 
ethical,  the  divine,  is  designed  for  it.  Although  the  divine 
love  imparts  many  and  various  blessings,  yet  the  ethical  God 
has  made  the  creature  an  end  worthy  of  love  only  by  assigning 
to  it  the  best  thing,  viz.  by  imparting  to  it  the  spirit  of  love. 


96  §  9.  god's  ideal  of  the  ethical  would. 

So  then  God  decrees  the  world  for  a  moral  end,  to  realize  the 
idea  and  honour  of  the  good,  which  He  loves  absolutely  in 
Himself,  which,  however,  must  not  remain  exhausted  in  His 
person,  but  which  is  in  Him  a  potency  for  something  else 
distinct  from  Himself.  He  decrees  a  world  outside  of  Him- 
self for  the  establishment  of  an  intercourse  of  love  and  for 
the  diffusion  of  the  life  of  love;  but  just  on  that  account  He 
wills  morality  as  the  world's  law  of  life,  and  as  its  nobility 
and  its  honour,  by  means  of  which  it  can  be  an  ultimate  end 
for  God,  the  very  image  of  God.  In  the  divine  will  that 
there  be  a  world  are  inseparably  joined  the  willing  of  the  Bo^a, 
of  God,  i.e.  idtimately,  the  glorifying  of  the  good  which  is 
identical  with  God,  and  the  willing  of  the  8o|a  of  the  world, 
in  particular,  of  the  rational  creature  on  the  earth,  man. 


§  9.   God's  Ideal  of  the  Mhical  World  in  general. 

In  order  to  will  an  ethical  world,  God  wills  a  natural  world, 
and  a  rational  or  personal  world,  including  a  multi- 
plicity of  persons,  who  are  distinct  and  relatively 
independent,  but  connected  together  by  the  idea  of 
morality.  The  natural  and  mental  multiplicity  of  the 
individuals  does  not  annul  the  common  element  in  their 
moral  endowment,  but  gives  to  this  endowment  the 
double  character  of  universality  and  of  individuality. 
Accordingly,  in  order  to  constitute  an  ethical  world 
there  must  be,  first,  nature ;  secondly,  rational  person- 
ality, both  of  these  in  the  double  character  of  likeness 
and  of  individuality  ;  thirdly,  the  union  and  blending  of 
the  natural  element  with  the  reason,  which  is  designed 
to  be  dominant.  The  attainment  of  the  last,  which  is 
the  goal,  will  be  conditioned  upon  a  moral  2>rocess,  in 
which,  by  means  of  riioral  agency,  nature  and  spirit  gain 
their  perfection  and  strength  each  for  itself,  and  also 
their  right  relation  to  each  other,  or  their  union,  which 
is  inseparable  from  their  normal  outworking.  But  in 
order  to  the  possibility  of  a  moral  process,  the  factors  of 


ANALOGY  BETWEEN  GOD  AND  THE  WOKLD,  97 

the  moral  world  can  be  united  at  first  only  in  a  separ- 
able form,  in  order  that  there  may  remain  room  for  a 
growth  of  this  nnion.  An  ideal  sundering  of  the 
elements  thus  loosely  bound  together  is  brought  about 
by  the  consciousness  of  an  obligation,  or  of  the  work 
to  be  done ;  yet  this  sundering  as  such  does  not  involve 
an  opposition  between  the  two  factors,  neither  an  actual 
separation  nor  a  spurious  combination,  but  only  the 
possibility  of  an  abnormal  development. 

Note. — In  the  thesis  religion  is  not  expressly  mentioned, 
but  it  has  its  place  in  the  rational  nature  of  man.  From 
this  point  of  view  it  will  appear  that  the  ethical  goal  is 
the  union  of  subjective  reason  not  merely  with  nature  or 
with  other  rational  natures,  but  also  with  God,  the  objective 
universal  reason. 

1.  The  thesis  aims  to  give  a  survey  of  the  factors  which 
constitute  the  fundamental  part  of  ethics,  and  which,  collec- 
tively taken,  involve  the  divinely-decreed  possibility  of  the 
realization  of  an  objective  moral  world.  First,  in  the  three 
main  points  which  go  to  constitute  the  moral  world,  answering 
to  the  Christian  idefl  of  man  as  made  in  the  image  of  God, 
the  analogy  with  the  nature  of  God  will  be  evident.  For  in 
God  there  are  physical  categories  or  attributes,  and  on  the 
other  hand  spiritual,  which,  however,  by  the  righteous  self- 
love  of  God  are  maintained  in  liarmonious  unison,  in  such  a 
manner  as  eternally  to  mediate  God's  holy  and  blessed  life  of 
love.  So,  likewise,  the  world  can  be  meant  to  be  a  moral 
world,  only  as  it  has  in  itself  (1)  a  natural  side ;  (2)  in 
relative  opposition  to  this  a  spiritual,  personal  side ;  but  (3) 
the  destination  and  capacity  perfectly  to  imite  the  two,  or,  in 
other  words,  to  reach  the  point  where  the  ethical  power  more 
and  more  gets  the  mastery  of  the  whole  man,  although,  to  be 
sure,  only  by  a  process  mediated  by  cognition  and  volition. 
Morality  in  God  cannot  be  essentially  other  than  the  morality 
designed  for  the  world  (§  7).  The  derivation  of  the  latter 
from  man's  resemblance  to  God,  which  was  argued  in  §  7 
and  8,  is  confirmed  by  the  general  conception  of  morality  as 
we  have  defined  it  in  §  2. 

2.  In  the  first  place,  a  necessary  factor  of  morality  in  a 

G 


9  8  §  9.    TEE  ETHICAL  WORLD  IN  GENERAL. 

world  is  nature.  This  is  so  not  merely  in  the  wider  sense 
that  man  is  first  of  all  a  being  made  or  born  through  natural 
forces,  that  even  man's  first  form  of  existence  is  itself  nature, 
since  he  is  not  yet  an  ethical  product  (except  as  proceeding 
from  God),  but  possesses  only  the  possibility  of  producing  what 
is  ethical,  and  also  of  becoming  himself  an  ethical  product. 
Eather,  this  also  is  meant,  that  a  nature  external  to  man  must 
be  given  him  for  his  ethical  purposes,  a  nature,  as  just  said, 
not  already  made  ethical,  but  yet  a  nature  capable  of  being 
moulded  and  put  to  ethical  uses  by  the  mind.  If  the  mind 
did  not  have  in  nature  a  material  on  which  it  could  act,  if  it 
were  without  nature,  then  minds  acting  on  one  another  would 
have  to  be  treated  as  mere  matter;  and  that  would  encroach 
on  freedom.  By  the  fact  that  created  minds  have  also  a 
nature  in  themselves,  it  is  possible  to  exert  an  influence  on 
them  which  does  not  simply  determine  them  and  reduce  them 
to  passiveness.  For  now  the  influence  is  directed  immedi- 
ately only  upon  the  natural  side  of  the  mind,  and  is  deposited 
in  this  as  in  an  indifferent  medium,  which  is  not  the  centre 
of  the  personality,  but  only  its  periphery.  And  so  the 
impression  from  without  can  indeed  work  upon  the  spirit  by 
way  of  solicitation  and  incitement,  but  without  determining  it 
compulsorily. 

The  same  law  also  governs  the  relation  of  God  to  men : 
God's  Spirit  works  upon  the  human  spirit  through  outward 
objective  things ;  the  means  of  grace  have  a  sensuous  element 
in  them ;  this  is  for  Protestantism  an  important  principle,  in 
opposition  to  all  the  subjectivism  of  so-called  enthusiasts  or 
fanatics.  Furthermore,  if  there  were  only  minds  and  no 
nature,  then  minds  could  objectify  themselves  only  in  minds ; 
and  ivorks,  as  the  aim  of  action,  could  not  come  to  an  outward 
independent  existence ;  work  and  worlcman  would  not  come 
to  be  clearly,  permanently  distinguished.  On  the  other  hand, 
nature  furnishes  the  concrete  basis  for  a  world  of  objective 
works,  of  products  of  an  impersonal  sort,  but  service- 
able to  personal  beings — for  a  connected  series  of  works, 
and  for  a  systematic  exercise  of  love.  Nature  accomplishes 
this,  to  be  sure,  only  by  its  capacity  of  expressing  what  is 
spiritual,  both  in  that  it  influences  man,  and  conveys  to  him, 
to    his    intelligence    and    fancy,   something    to   occupy   and 


NECESSITY  OF  NATUKE  IN  THE  MOEAL  WOELD.  99 

stimulate  him,  and  also  in  that  it  is  a  susceptible  material 
which  can  be  wrought  upon  by  the  plastic  faculty  of  the 
mind,  by  its  representing  and  organizing  activity.^  Although, 
therefore,  in  relation  to  morality,  nature  is  to  be  always 
merely  a  means,  yet,  from  what  has  been  said,  it  is  evident 
how  the  domain  of  morals  is  enriched  by  it.  And  although 
nature,  in  its  empirical  character,  cannot  be  deduced  a  ■priori, 
yet  it  is  plain  both  that,  in  order  to  ethical  activity,  an  object 
on  which  the  mind  can  work,  a  material  substance,  is  necessary, 
and  also  that  the  nature  which  we  know  from  experience 
answers  to  this  need.  Ethics  long  remained  dry  and  lifeless 
in  relation  to  everything  which  goes  beyond  interior  ethics, 
because  a  spiritualistic  depreciation  of  nature  and  of  the  body 
was  dominant.  If  the  real  facts  of  moral  life  are  to  be 
profitably  portrayed,  ethics  must  also  take  in  the  material 
world,  as  one  element  in  relation  to  what  morality  has  to 
accomplish, — in  relation  to  moral  action  and  work  on  earth, — 
although  we  must  not  go  so  far  as  to  regard  ruling  over 
nature,  or  the  transforming  of  matter  into  spirit,  as  the  thing 
which  morality  is  to  accomplish.  Nature  is  itself  an  ethical 
product  of  God,  good,  that  is,  metaphysically  good ;  and  this 
its  metaphysical  goodness  stands  in  intimate  alliance  with  the 
ethical  good  which  is  to  be  worked  out  with  its  help.  In 
nature  the  ethical  element  in  mind  can  at  any  time  make 
itself  a  conscious  reality,  in  that  mind  elaborates,  organizes, 
assimilates  it,  and  makes  it  subserve  ethical  ends,  according  to 
its  divinely-ordained  purpose. 

'  [These  terms  are  borrowed  from  Sclileiermacher,  wlio  classifies  all  moral 
activity  as  reinigend  or  wiedcrherstellend  (purifying  or  restoring),  verbrtitend  or 
eriueiternd  (extending  or  diffusing),  and  darsiellend  (representing,  exhibiting). 
So  especially  in  his  Chrisfliche  Sitte.  The  phrase  organisirend ,  used  here  b)' 
Dorner,  is  also  taken  from  Sclileiermacher,  who  employs  it  in  his  Philofiophische 
Ethik  in  a  sense  similar  to  that  of  verbreitend  in  the  other  work.  Dorner 
elsewhere  uses  verbreitend  and  erweiternd  also.  The  reinigende  Handeln  refere 
to  the  activity  whose  aim  is  to  purge  away  the  impure  elements  that  inhere 
in  the  moral  life.  The  verbreitende  Handeln  denotes  the  activity  by  which  the 
ethical  community  Avorks  by  way  of  propagating  the  moral  life.  The  darstel- 
lende  Handeln  denotes  that  sphere  of  activity  whose  aim  and  eflfect  is  to 
manifest  the  inward  moral  life  ;  this  embraces,  e.g.,  outward  acts  of  worship, 
religious  art,  etc.  Bildend,  above  rendered  "plastic,"  is  used  also  by  Schleier- 
macher  in  his  Philosophische  Ethik  as  =  organisirend,  and  as  contrasted  with 
the  erkennende  (cognitive)  function.  It  embraces  the  verbreitend  and  the 
darstellend.     Cf.  §  82.— Tk.] 


100  §  9.    THE  ETHICAL  WORLD  IN  GENEKAL 

Note.  —  Sclileiermacher,  in  Lis  Monologues,  enthusiastically 
eulogizes  the  independence  of  nature  and  the  outer  world  which 
Lelougs  to  the  mind  in  its  moral  self-culture,  and  holds  that 
the  mind  can  for  its  development  dispense  with  the  outward 
world,  if  the  latter  is  unpropitious,  since  it  is  able,  by  means 
of  its  fancy,  to  represent  to  itself  the  most  manifold  moral 
relations,  inwardly  to  take  a  position  with  reference  to  them, 
and  thus  to  increase  its  moral  strength.  In  this  it  is  to  be 
recognised,  as  a  merit,  that  he  emphasizes  mind  as  an  inde- 
pendent thing  over  against  nature.  But  the  fancy,  without 
experience,  would  not  be  able  to  imagine  a  multiplicity  of 
moral  relations.  Again,  such  an  inward  attitude  taken  towards 
imagined  relations  could  scarcely  be  called  real  moral  activity. 
The  will  directed  to  this  would  hardly  be  distinguishable  from 
mere  thought  or  purpose.  But  inward  purpose  can  by  no 
means  be  made  to  take  the  place  of  real  outward  action. 
Moral  strength  is  put  to  the  test  in  the  world  of  reality  quite 
otherwise  than  in  that  of  fancy ;  and  so  also  the  obstacles  of  a 
real  sort  to  be  overcome  are  of  a  wholly  different  nature  from 
tlie  difficulties  which  are  merely  conceived  of.^  In  order  that 
the  good  may  not  be  a  mere  appearance,  may  not  have  a 
sliadowy  existence,  but  that  the  ethical  spirit  may  be  able  to 
frame  for  itself  a  fitting  body,  yes,  shape  an  actual  moral  world, 
tliere  must  be  given  to  it  an  actual  reality,  an  existent  thing, 
which  at  first  is  not  yet  ethical,  is  not  yet  determined  by  man's 
will,  but  is  ccqjablc  of  being  determined — a  pre-ethical  substance, 
matter  in  the  wider  sense,  which  includes  not  merely  the 
materia  hruta,  but  also  something  living  and  spiritual,  which, 
as  being  a  created  thing,  is  plastic.  This  pre-ethical  reality, 
which  can  be,  and  is,  moulded  for  moral  ends,  is  therefore  by  no 
means  something  which,  so  far  as  morality  is  concerned,  can  be 
dispensed  with.  There  must  be  found,  even  in  this  nature 
given  to  man,  also  a  minimum  at  least  of  the  union  of  nature 
and  spirit,  enough  to  constitute  a  ground  for  the  suscepti- 
bility of  nature  to  spiritual  influence.  The  possibility  of 
this  lies  in  the  simple  fact  that  nature,  even  matter,  cannot 
be  absolutely  foreign  to  spirit,  for  it  can  be  transformed  into 
thought. 

^  [This  is  not  said  in  Disposition  merely  to  a  pure  idealism,  which  transforms 
nature  into  spirit,  but,  as  is  self-evident,  it  applies  likewise  to  a  psychological 
sensualism,  which  would  recognise  only  "  appearances  "  in  the  mind,  and  thus 
does  not  get  to  an  objective  world  ; — i.e.  it  applies  to  a  "  doctrine  of  the  soul 
without  a  soul,"  as  Kibot  exjiresses  it.  For  then,  too,  we  have  to  do  merely  with 
plienomenal  images  in  the  soul,  without  being  sure  even  that  there  is  a  soul. 
Of  this  nature  also  is  the  view  of  Hipolyte  Taine,  De  V Intelligence,  so  far  as 
he  does  not  embrace  materialism,  which  he  again,  however,  analyzes  into 
sensualism.  — Ed.  ] 


THE  MATEFJALISTIC  DOCTRINE.  101 

3.  The  mental  world  in  general. 

Morality  indeed  would  be  still  more  out  of  the  question,  if 
there  were  nothing  but  nature,  or  even  nothing  but  matter. 
Without  reason,  which  represents  what  is  absolutely  good  and 
morally  necessary,  there  would  be  only  either  caprice  and 
chance,  or  a  necessity  of  a  physical  fatalistic  sort,  destitute 
of  teleological  import.  But  this  necessity,  being  without  a 
ground,  would  itself  again  be  ultimately  nothing  but  chance. 
In  view  of  the  spread  of  a  materialistic  mode  of  thought  at 
the  present  time,  it  is  perhaps  suitable  to  dwell  a  little  upon 
it,  and  consider,  first,  what  it  posits  and  aims  at,  and,  secondly, 
wdiat  its  scientific  value  is. 

The  doctrine  of  materialism  is  this :  There  exists  nothing 
except  matter,  but  no  spirit  as  a  specific  principle  distinct 
from  matter.  As  Leibnitz  holds  the  material  monads  to  bo 
dormant  confined  spirit,  and  Schelling  holds  them  to  be  esjprit 
gcU,  i.e.  only  spirit  in  a  different  form,  so  vice  versa  the 
materialist  would  have  it  that  only  matter  and  not  spirit 
exists.  But  matter  he  conceives  of  as  atoms,  or  primordial 
particles  of  infinite  smallness,  which  have  been  from  eternity, 
and  are  always  and  indestructibly  the  same,  but  which  when 
united  with  force — yet  according  to  given  conditions,  for 
instance,  the  proximity  or  distance  of  other  particles — pro- 
duce various  phenomena.  For  the  comprehension  of  the  world 
the  hypothesis  of  these  atoms  or  molecules  suffices.  Out  of 
them  everything  which  is  builds  itself  up  spontaneously,  whether 
these  atoms  be  conceived  of  as  from  the  beginning  individually 
different,  with  different  affinities  for  one  another,  or  whether 
they  be  conceived  of  as  all  in  themselves  alike,  but  endowed 
with  an  infinite  variety  of  forces, — of  possible  functions,  by 
means  of  which  they  can  enter  into  the  most  manifold  com- 
binations with  other  atoms,  according  as  a  moving  impetus  is 
somehow  accidentally  given  to  them.  The  efficient  causes 
which  serve  to  explain  single  phenomena  may,  indeed,  accord- 
ing to  materialism,  be  inquired  after,  but  not  the  final 
causes  or  purposes  through  which  the  things,  the  efficient 
causes  or  atoms,  are  regulated  and  set  in  motion,  and  also 
receive  their  direction.  Teleology,  or  the  notion  of  design, 
counts  with  it  for  a  mere  subjective  conception  and 
appendage.     The   objective   state   of    the    fact    is    only   that 


102  §  9.    THE  ETHICAL  WORLD  IN  GENERAL. 

everything  happens  as  it  does  according  to  physical 
necessity ;  that  all  things,  just  as  they  are,  are  to  be  looked 
upon  as  being  good,  or  as  of  equal  value  ;  and  that  only 
a  subjective  valuation  is  left  for  us.  Organism  has  come 
about  only  by  the  necessary  activity  of  the  atoms,  and  is  a 
combination  of  them  by  virtue  of  general  physical,  mechanical, 
chemical  \a,ws. 

Also  for  the  explanation  of  the  origin  of  vegetable,  animal, 
and  even  human  forms,  materialism  holds  that  it  is  not  neces- 
sary to  go  back  to  a  spiritual  princij)le,  which  conducts  a 
process  according  to  a  purpose,  or  which  inserts  itself  into 
matter.  It  is  not  even  necessary  to  assume  a  vital  or  physical 
force,  different  from  mechanism,  since  it  is  hoped  rather  by 
means  of  the  correlation  of  forces,  to  trace  everything,  heat, 
electricity,  magnetism,  galvanism,  and  life,  back  to  mechanism. 
Man  is,  to  be  sure,  also  a  thinking  thing ;  but  that  means 
only  that  the  body,  especially  by  reason  of  phosphorus,  is  a 
thinking  machine,  which  secretes  thoughts  as  well  as  other 
things.  The  soul  is  not  a  substance  existing  by  itself,  but 
only  an  action  of  the  material  particles,  a  collective  name 
for  functions  of  matter.  Tor  mental  action  there  is  no  other 
real  substratum  than  matter ;  what  exists  is  only  the  brain 
with  its  nervous  vibrations.  The  whole  constitution  and 
history  of  individuals  and  of  mankind  is  explained  by  the 
co-operation  of  air,  light,  and  food, — in  short,  by  changes  in 
matter.^ 

•  This  is  essentially  the  view  of  Karl  Vogt,  Kohlerglauhe  unci  Wissenschaft, 
1855.  B'dder  aus  deni  Thierlehen.  Jacob  Moleschott,  Physiologle  des  Stoff- 
wechsels  in  PJlanzen  und  Thiere.n,  1851.  Der  Kreislauf  des  Lebens  [5th  ed. 
1875-78].  L.  Biidmer,  Kraft  und  Stoff,  1855  [15th  ed.  1883].  E.  H.  Hiickel, 
Naturliche  SchopfungsgeschicJde  [7th  ed.  1879].  Generelle  Morphologie,  1866. 
Anthropogenie,  1874.  Oskar  Schmidt,  Descendeiizlehre,  1873.  F.  Albert 
Lange,  Geschichte  des  Materialismus  und  Kritik  seiner  Bedeutung  fiir  die 
Gegenwart,  1866,  3rd  ed.  1876.  Auguste  Comte,  Cours  de  ]}hilosophie  jMsitive, 
1830-42  [4th  ed.  1877],  6  vols.  Systime  de  jjolitique  positive  and  Traite  de 
sociologie  instituante  la  rdligion  de  V Humanite,  T.  i.  1851,  and  his  most  pro- 
minent disciple  Littr6,  who  has  written  his  biography.  Allied  to  Comte  is 
John  Stuart  Mill,  who  again  recognises  a  real  Deity,  but  will  accord  to  him 
neither  omnipotence  nor  omniscience.  [Against  Mill,  M'Cosh,  Exajninatioii 
of  J.  S.  Mill's  Philosophy,  1866,  2nd  ed.  1877.  David  Masson,  Peccnt  British 
Philosophy,  1865.  Against  Comte  and  Mill,  cf.  also  Dilthey,  Einleitung  in  die 
Geisteswissenschaften,!.  132  sqq.,  1883.— Herbert  Spencer,  A  System  of  Synthetic 
Philosophy,  Part  I.  First  Principhs  of  a  New  System  of  Philosophy.    Spencer, 


THE  MATERIALISTIC  DOCTRINE  EXAMINED.  103 

In  forming  a  jitdgmcnt  of  materialism,  first,  its  scientific 
merit  must  be  taken  into  view,  and  secondly,  it  must  be  con- 
sidered what  consequences  follow  from  it  with  reference  to 
the  domain  of  morality. 

{a)  Materialism  is  an  inadequate  hypothesis.     For  it  is  not 

however,  is  not  a  consistent  materialist.— Ed. ]  Finally,  Darwin,  Origin  of 
Speciflv  [6th  ed.  1872].  Among  the  opponents  of  this  materialistic  drift  are  to 
.be  mentioned  :  Trendelenburg,  who  in  his  Loglsche  UntersucJiungen,  2nd  ed. 
vol.  ii.  pp.  1-77,  gives  the  most  thorough  discussion  of  the  notion  of  design 
and  of  its  rightfulness.  [Janet,  TraifA  de  philosophie,  1 880.  Les  caitsesjinales, 
1876.  Le  cerveau  et  la  pensde. — Ed.]  Further,  Duke  of  Argyll,  The  Beign  of 
Laro  [5th  ed.  1870].  Wigand,  Der  Darwini'imiis,  1874.  R.  Schmidt,  Darwin- 
ische  Theorieen,  etc.,  1876.  Lotze,  Mikrokosrnos  [3rd  ed.  1876-80],  vol.  i.  Bk.  iii. 
chap.  4  (on  the  life  of  matter  as  a  jihenomenon  of  the  supersensuous  ;  the  inde- 
pendence of  the  soul ;  the  want  of  independence  in  all  mechanisms,  which  exist 
as  the  teleological  framework  for  intellectual  forces,  especially  morality). — Fabri, 
Briefe  gegen  den  MaMriallsmuti,  1856.  Schaller,  Leib  und  Seele,  zur  Aiif- 
klarung  i'lber  Kohlergluuhe  und  Naturivissenschaft,  1856.  Michelis,  Der  kirch- 
liche  Sfandjmnkt  in  der  Naturforschung.  Hubcr,  Die  Forschung  nach  der 
Materie,  1877.  Frohschammer,  Chrii^tenthvm  vndmoderne  Xaturivissenschaft, 
1868.  Zockler,  Theologie  iind  Xaturiviisenscha/t,  vol.  ii.,  1879,  p.  397  sqq. 
'EhraYd,  Apiologetik.  Ulrici,  GottunddieNatur.  Ha-rms,  Abhandlungen,  1868, 
pp.  209-277.  Snell,  Die  Streitfrage  des  Materialismus,  1858.  Pressense,  Die 
Ursprimge,  translated  from  the  French  by  Fabarius.  [On  Darwinism,  see  also 
the  literature  below,  §  10,  15. — Ed.] 

[Addition  by  the  translator.  Of  the  above-mentioned  works  the  following 
have  been  translated  :  Biichner,  Force  and  Matter,  translated  by  J.  F.  Colliug- 
wood  (London,  2nd  ed.  1870).  Hackel,  The  Hintory  of  Creation,  translation, 
revised  by  E.  E.  Lankester  (London  ]876).  The  Evolution  of  Man  (London 
1879).  Ed.  Oskar  Schmidt,  The  Doctrine  of  Descent  and  Darivinism,  Interna- 
tional Scientific  Series,  vol.  xii.,  1872.  F.  A.  Lange,  History  of  Materialism, 
etc.,  translated  by  E.  C.  Thomas  (English  and  Foreign  Philosophical  Library, 
1877).  Comte,  The  Positive  Philosophy  of  A.  Comte  freely  translated  and 
condensed,  by  H.  Martineau  (2nd  ed.  Loudon  1875).  System  of  Positive  Polity, 
translated  by  J.  H.  Bridges  (London  1875-77).  Janet,  Final  Causes,  trans- 
lated from  the  2nd  ed.  by  W.  Affleck  (Edinburgh:  T.  &  T.  Clark,  1883). 
Lotze,  Microcosmiis,  an  Essay  concerning  Man  and  his  Relation  to  the  World, 
translated  by  Elizabeth  Hamilton  and  E.  E.  C.  Jones  (Edinburgh :  T.  &  T. 
Clark,  1885).  R.  Schmidt,  Theories  of  Darwin,  translated  by  G.  A.  Zimmer- 
man, Chicago  1883:  James  M'Clure  &  Co.  Pressense,  A  Study  of  Origins 
(Ijondon  1883).  The  following  among  the  many  English  works  may  be 
mentioned  :  B.  P.  Bowne,  The  Philosophy  of  HerheH  Spencer  (New  York 
1874).  Studies  in  Theism,  1879.  T.  E.  Birks,  3Iodern  Physical  Fatalism, 
including  an  Examination  of  Herbert  Spencer  n  First  Principles  (2nd  ed.  1882). 
W.  M.  J^acy,  An  Exainination  of  the  Philosophy  of  the  Unknoivahle  as  ex- 
pounded by  Herbert  Spencer,  1873.  Asa  Gray,  Darwiniana,  1876.  James 
Martineau,  Modern  Materialism,  1876.  Duke  of  Argyll,  The  Unity  of  Nature, 
1884.  Anonymous,  The  Final  Science,  a  satire  on  materialism  (New  York 
1885).] 


104  §  9.    THE  ETHICAL  WORLD  IN  GENERAL. 

able  to  explain  important  facts,  which  it  must  let  stand,  but 
which  contradict  it.  A  great  part  of  the  phenomena,  and 
those  the  most  important,  it  does  not  explain  as  it  promised, 
but  knows  only  enough  to  ignore  or  to  deny  them.  Thus  it 
is  not  able  to  explain  how  the  unity  of  an  organism  remains 
identical  amidst  the  change  of  particles,  but  must  simply  let 
life  stand  as  an  unexplained  fact.^  Since  according  to  it  all 
plienomena  are  built  wp  from  atoms,  it  must  deny  that  living 
forms  are  self-contained  and  self -maintaining  individuals. 
Just  as  little  can  it  explain  sensation,  this  relation  of  a  living 
unit  to  itself;  for  it  cannot  recognise  any  such  unit.  The 
single  atoms,  phosphorus,  oxygen,  etc.,  have  no  sensation. 
Their  combination,  too,  is  according  to  materialism  no  unit 
which  can  be  sensible  of  itself,  is  no  reality  in  itself,  but  at 
the  most  a  relation  of  single  insensitive  atoms  to  one  another, 
from  which  a^ain  no  sensation  can  result. 

The  case  is  similar  with  self-consciousness,  which  it  has 
to  let  stand  as  an  undeniable,  though  troublesome,  enigma.'' 
Lotze  says  justly,  self-consciousness  is  never  conceivable  as 
the  product  of  interaction  in  a  multiplicity  of  things,  but  only 
as  the  utterance  of  an  indivisible  being.  And  suppose  this 
knowledge  of  the  ego  in  self-consciousness  were  an  error,  yet 
this  error,  being  a  universal  mental  fact,  would  need  to  be  ex- 
plained instead  of  being  ignored.  But  in  general,  materialism 
is  involved  in  the  inconsistency  of  letting  mental  functions 
stand  as  facts,  which  again  by  its  view  of  things  it  is  logically 
required  to  annul.  Carried  out  consistently,  it  is  an  absolute 
denial  of  mind ;  and  yet  it  will  not  confess  that  it  cannot  set 
aside  mental  functions,  nay,  that  without  the  function  of 
thought,  however  perversely  it  may  use  that  function,  it  itself 
would  not  be.  In  truth,  it  is  in  principle  the  denial  of  all 
mental  functions,  for  it  reduces  everything  to  merely  material 
functions;  but  in  order  to  do  this,  it  must  eliminate  from 
them  what  yet  essentially  belongs  to  them,  especially  the 
identity  of  the  self-consciousness  accompanying  them  in  every 
change  of  material.  Its  own  doctrine,  moreover,  it  is  not 
able  to  prove ;  it  is  down  to  its  ultimate  principles   a   mere 

^  Schaller,  I.e.  p.  158  sq. 

2  As  Dii  Bois  Rejnuond  has  acknowledged  in  his  famous  address  ;  cf.  Lotze, 
Ilikrokosmus,  i.  pp.  176,  386  sq.     [Englisli  translation,  i.  158,  344  sq.] 


THE  MATERIALISTIC  DOCTRINE  EXAMINED.  105 

hypothesis,  which  does  not  do  what  is  to  be  demanded  of  a 
hypothesis,  namely,  explain  the  obvious  facts.  Only  the 
senses  are  made  the  source  of  knowledge  ;  yet  the  materialist's 
atoms  themselves  are  not  perceptible  by  the  senses,  but,  be- 
cause they  are  infinitely  small,  are  apprehensible  only  by 
thought,  and  so  far  forth  are  only  objects  of  intelligence  ; 
about  their  whence,  whither,  wherefore,  materialism  is  able  to 
make  no  scientific  statement.  In  addition  to  this,  it  by  no 
means  follows,  from  the  fact  that  matter  is  said  to  consist  of 
atoms,  that  they  alone  exist,  and  no  mind ;  there  are  also 
opponents  of  materialism,  as  Lotze,  Sigwart,^  who  incline  to 
the  atomic  theory. 

(/>)  But  almost  more  important  is  the  significance  of 
materialism  in  reference  to  the  domain  of  morality.  For  it 
is  obliged  to  deny  human  freedom,  every  universally  binding 
moral  law,  yes,  every  universal  truth,  and  to  divest  the  world 
of  everything  in  it  that  has  value.  Vogt  says,  there  is  no  such 
thing  as  free  will,  hence,  too,  no  accountability,  such  as  moral 
science  and  the  administration  of  criminal  law  would  impose 
upon  us ;  we  are  at  no  instant  masters  of  ourselves  and  of  our 
faculties,  nor,  therefore,  of  the  so-called  reason.  Where  free 
self-determination  of  the  mind  is  impossible,  there,  too,  punish- 
ableness  and  punishment  are  abrogated ;  in  case  of  accelerated 
change  of  particles,  too,  punishment  would  not  even  hit  its 
proper  object.  In  place  of  the  delusion  of  free  self-deter- 
mination, materialism  exhorts  us  to  put  the  consciousness  of 
necessity,  as  if  the  consciousness  of  a  necessity  did  not  itself 
presuppose  in  turn  the  consciousness  of  a  freedom.^  For  that 
which  we  must  of  absolute  necessity  do,  \vould  no  longer  appear 
to  us  necessary  if  we  had  no  knowledge  of  freedom.  To  the 
doctrine  that  there  is  only  matter  and  no  mind,  that  man  is 
wholly  dependent  on  the  motion  of  matter,  even  Plato,  in  his 
day,  opposed  the  fact  that  man  can  set  himself  against  his  body 
and  its  impulses  ;  if  the  soul  were  only  the  sum  or  the  product 
of  the  body,  and  not  an  independent  thing,  how  comes  it,  he 
asks,  that  the  soul  can  rule  the  body  ? 

According  to  Vogt,  morality  and  its  idealism   become   an 

'  Jahrbiichcr  far   detitsche    Theologie,   iv.    p.   271    sq.      Zur   Apologie   des 
Atoinismus. 

^  Sclialler,  I.e.,  Abschnitt  iv.  p.  43. 


106  §  9.    THE  ETHICAL  WOELD  IN  GENERAL. 

illusion,  which  he  has  no  means  of  distinguishing  from  selfish- 
ness. Lange,  Carneri,  and  others  talk  of  an  ethical  materialism  : 
benevolence,  sympathy,  social  tendencies,  they  say,  are  founded 
in  nature  itself,  as  the  very  animal  world  shows.  But  these 
affections  do  not  amount  to  pure  love,  but  only  to  a  higher 
form  of  selfishness.  Materialism,  engrossed  with  the  details  of 
sensuous  functions,  can  recognise  no  universal,  and  absolutely 
valuable,  spiritual  good.  It  holds  that  to  be  good  which  is 
useful,  and  which  corresponds  to  given  conditions.  But  since 
materialism,  according  to  its  principles,  must  deny  the  moral 
realm  itself,  here  is  the  point  where  it  stumbles  upon  conscience, 
and,  if  it  adheres  to  itself,  becomes  unmoral,  becomes  spiritual 
suicide,  the  murder  of  conscience.  It  is  possible  to  attempt  to 
discard  morality,  but  morality  does  not  let  itself  be  discarded. 
It  is  impossible  for  man  to  be  destitute  of  reference  to  moral 
good  ;  the  law  is  laid  upon  him  that  he  must  be  connected  with 
the  idea  of  morality,  at  least  iu  an  immoral  way,  if  he  will  not 
l3e  so  in  a  moral  way.  At  this  point  there  is  only  one  moral 
decision — for  or  against.  And  materialism,  according  to  its  own 
principles,  must  also  concede  the  power  of  the  moral  sense  to 
decide  us  against  materialism  ;  for,  according  to  its  own  theory, 
if  we  thus  decide,  we  do  so,  as  we  do  everything,  of  necessity. 
But  if  it  demands  of  the  will,  as  it  also  does,  to  follow  it  as  a  new 
evangel,  it  falls  at  once  out  of  its  role,  and  has  recourse  to  a 
principle  which  overturns  materialism  itself.  It  has  recourse 
to  free  will  and  a  universal  law,  a  universal  truth,  the  know- 
ledge of  which  is  a  universal  duty,  while  at  the  same  time 
it  denies  everything  spiritual  and  universal. 

The  case  is  similar  with  other  contradictions  made  by 
materialism.  On  the  one  hand,  it  denies  all  freedom,  and 
insists  on  physical  necessitarianism,  and  therefore  would  have 
to  deem  tyranny  or  ahsohdisin  justifiable  wherever  this  is  found; 
but,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  accustomed  to  wave  the  banner  of 
extreme  liberty.  All  2)umshment,  even  that  for  murder,  it 
designates  as  an  unjust  invention  of  the  majority  made  on  their 
own  behalf;  on  the  other  hand,  the  judges  who  pronounce 
sentence  of  death,  it  does  not  excuse,  as  according  to  its 
doctrine  of  universal  necessity  it  ought  to  do,  but  actually 
calls  them  criminals.  Likewise  it  preaches  irrogress,  the  shaking 
off  of  all  superstition  and  all  fetters,  and  it  imagines  itself  to 


THE  MATERIALISTIC  DOCTRINE  EXAMINED.  107 

be  in  tlie  front  rank  of  progress.  But  in  truth  it  is  absolute 
stability ;  there  is  nothing  left  to  it  but  the  atoms  and  their 
aimless  motion.  By  reducing  everything  to  rotation  and  change 
of  particles,  it  divests  history  of  all  meaning  and  aim.  It  will 
not  be  dependent  upon  ideas  and  ideals :  therefore,  instead  of 
that,  it  must  be  in  slavish  dependence  upon  matter.  For 
necessity  is  more  degrading  and  depressing  in  materialism  than 
vi^ith  Spinoza.  He  secures  to  the  individual,  as  over  against 
other  things,  a  sort  of  independence,  by  the  dependence  of 
everything  upon  substance,  while  materialism  makes  the  whole 
man  dependent  upon  matter  and  change  in  matter. 

Materialism  does  not  see  what  even  the  Pythagoreans  saw 
when  opposing  the  Ionic  Hylozoists,  namely,  that  the  main 
thing  in  the  cosmos  is  not  matter,  but  the  forming  and  shaping 
of  matter  —  the  formative  principle.  This  principle  might, 
with  greater  justice  than  matter,  be  called  the  essential  thing 
in  the  notion  of  the  world,  since  matter,  as  something 
material,  exists  for  the  sake  of  the  self-manifestation  of  the 
formative  principle.  If,  now,  materialism  does  not  insist  on 
being  simply  silent  about  this  which  is  of  most  importance,  of 
most  value,  namely,  the  fashioning  of  the  world,  its  harmonious 
teleological  order  ;  then,  since  design,  if  not  universally,  yet 
irresistibly,  obtrudes  itself,  the  materialist  must  transfer  rational, 
mysterious  purposes,  the  power  of  thought,  to  the  atoms  them- 
selves, which  are  his  efficient  causes,  and  make  them  intelli- 
gences. If  this  is  done  in  a  monistic  way,  or  so  that  matter 
in  itself  and  as  such  is  to  have  this  power  working  teleologically, 
then  we  have  in  matter  latent  mind,  tlie  monads  of  Leibnitz,  to 
which  Czolbe  would  lead  us.  Or  else,  in  addition  to  matter  a 
second  principle,  force,  must  be  required,  which  joins  itself  to 
matter — a  force  which,  in  order  to  explain  the  phenomena, 
must  participate  in  intelligence ;  but  this  force  is  then  itself 
again  a  substance,  and  only  another  name  for  soul. 

To  sum  up  all,  then,  materialism  is  equivalent  to  a  reduction 
of  the  cosmos  to  what  is  absolutely  elementary,  to  atoms  or 
primordial  elements  which  work  aimlessly,  mechanically,  and 
yet  necessarily,  and  wliich  alone  are  supposed  to  have  actual 
being.  For  with  its  mechanical  way  of  thinking,  it  must  simply 
ignore  the  living  individual  forms,  which,  amid  change  of  matter, 
maintain  their  identity,  and  present  themselves  to  us  as  units 


108  §  9.    THE  ETHICAL  WORLD  IN  GENERAL. 

ruled  by  a  purpose.  Just  so  with  sensibility,  thought,  self- 
consciousness,  will,  the  whole  world  of  history ;  materialism 
annihilates  the  cosmos  no  less  than  in  its  way  absolute  idealism 
does,  and  there  remains  for  it  only  a  whirling  chaos  of  atoms, 
without  goal,  aim,  intelligence,  without  mind,  without  virtue, 
without  God/  The  attempts  to  derive  something  spiritual 
from  motion,  especially  the  so-called  reflex  motion  and  its 
various  sorts,  by  which,  according  to  the  law  of  the  equivalence 
of  forces,  the  same  matter,  e.g.  ether,  is  said  to  become  warmth, 
electricity,  magnetism,  etc.,  furnish  anything  rather  than  evi- 
dence for  materialism.  They  lead,  at  the  most,  to  distant 
analogies,  but  in  all  these  motions  there  is  nothing  of  life,  of 
thought,  of  self-consciousness. 

So  then  materialism  must  recognise  a  formative  principle 
lying  outside  of  it ;  and  that  principle  is  mind,  the  thinking  and 
acting  force.  Yet  this  force  is  not  to  be  conceived  of  as  being 
at  bottom  merely  matter  or  nature ;  for  then  there  would  still 
be  no  real  distinction  between  mind  and  nature;  mind  would  be 
nothing  but  conscious  and  willing  nature,  and  would  itself  be  lost 
in  being  the  consciousness  and  mirror  of  nature.  If  mind  is  to  be 
distinguished  from  nature,  it  must  also  know  itself  as  mind,  and 
must  be  something  as  mind;  it  must  be  able  to  distinguish  itself 
from  nature,  and  to  put  itself  over  against  nature.  Not  till  it 
possesses  itself  as  mind,  and  is  itself  the  contents  of  its  conscious- 
ness and  will,  does  it  cease  to  be  overwhelmed  by  the  nature 
which  fills  it.  But  it  is  a  substance  by  itself,  different  from 
nature,  if  it  apprehends  itself  not  merely  as  turned  towards 
nature,  but  also  in  its  own  independence,  that  is,  if  it  is 
endowed  with  a  world  of  ideas  which  can  be  developed  by  it — 
a  world  of  eternal  truths,  to  which  also  belong  God  and  divine 
things. 

4.  By  claiming  both  a  natural  and  a  spiritual  side  for  the 
moral  equipment  of  man,  two  fundamental  heresies  in  morals 
are  excluded — spiritualism  or  idealism,  which  would  recognise 

1  "With  this  agrees  the  academical  address  of  Du  Bois  Reyraond,  Die  sieben 
Weltrathsd,  1880.  Cf.  Deutsche  Rumhchau,  Sept.  18S1,  and  Edmond  de 
Pressense,  Die  Ursprunge,  iibersetzt  von  Fabarins,  1884.  [In  Eng.,  A  Study 
of  Origins,  Lond.  1883.]  As  unexplained  enigmas  Du  Bois  Rej'mond  gives  :  The 
essence  of  matter  and  of  force,  the  origin  of  motion  and  of  life,  the  apparently 
intentional  contrivances  in  nature,  the  origin  of  simple  sensation,  of  thought  and 
self-consciousness,  and  of  freedom  of  will. 


RELATION  OF  THE  NATURAL  TO  THE  SPIRITUAL.  109 

only  the  rational  side  as  existent,  and  materialism.  Eather, 
both  sides  belong  together  :  but  how  ?  They  cannot  stand 
side  by  side  indifferent  and  without  relation  to  each  other  ; 
in  order  to  constitute  the  human  unit,  they  must  have  an 
inward  connection.  On  the  other  hand,  they  cannot  be 
regarded  as  of  equal  value  or  co-ordinate,  but,  without  losing 
their  difference,  must  have  rank  and  place  appropriate  to 
their  essential  character.  But  this  is  the  subordination  of  the 
physical  element  to  the  spiritual,  especially  to  the  ethical. 
The  inward  connection  is  to  be  manifested  in  the  fact  that 
each  of  the  two,  the  natural  side  and  the  rational  side,  is 
hy  virtue  of  its  own  nature  hrought  into  relation  to  the  other. 
The  rational  side,  which,  by  virtue  of  its  moral  destination,  or 
by  virtue  of  its  very  nature,  first  apprehends  itself  through 
law,  points  of  itself  to  the  natural  side  as  that  which  is 
to  be  shaped  by  its  standard.  Forma  apijctit  materiam. 
The  natural  side  in  man  points  of  itself  to  the  rational 
side :  for,  as  plastic  material,  it  awaits  the  activity  and 
shaping  power  of  the  latter.  Materia  appetit  formam.  For 
the  unifying  of  the  two  through  consciousness  and  will  is  the. 
moral  work  to  be  done  ;  and  this  is  attainable  only  by  means 
of  that  full  efficiency  of  the  spiritual  side  of  the  personality 
which  is  the  result  of  moral  self-cultivation  in  fellowship  with 
God.  The  perfection  of  both  sides,  however,  and  their  com- 
plete union,  cannot  come  immediately  from  nature  through 
the  act  of  creation,  but  is  an  ethical  product,  in  which  the 
act  and  freedom  of  man  must  participate.  The  union  of  the 
mind  with  nature  and  with  God  lies  in  man  only  as  a 
possibility  ;  and  the  rise  of  the  idea  of  morality  in  the  mind 
has  by  no  means  as  its  immediate  consequence  the  realiza- 
tion of  the  ethical  end  ;  knowledge  does  not  work  necessitat- 
ingly  upon  the  will.  Nature  and  spirit  do  not  immediately 
by  physical  necessity  adjust  themselves  to  the  consciousness 
of  law  ;  and  this  fact  is  not  to  be  regarded  as  an  evil ;  for 
otherwise  there  would  be  no  place  for  free  decision  in  favour 
of  the  good. 

The  connection  of  nature  and  mind  is  therefore  at  the 
outset  necessarily  of  that  sort  which  still  leaves  room  for  not 
merely  a  single  but  a  double  possibility  :  for  the  normal  one, 
foretokened  by  the  very  notion  of  nature  and  mind,  and  for 


110  §  9.    THE  ETHICAL,  WORLD  IN  GE^'ERAL. 

the  abnormal  one.  The  original  union  is  merely  a  dissoluble 
union.  The  abnormal  possibility  is  itself  again  of  a  twofold 
sort :  either  the  divorce  of  nature  from  the  rule  of  the  mind, 
i.e.  the  dominion  of  nature  over  mind ;  or  the  estrangement  of 
the  mind  from  nature,  a  merely  negative  relation  to  nature. 
The  latter  belongs  to  the  category  of  spiritualistic  heresy,  the 
former  to  that  of  materialistic  heresy.  Together  with  the 
possibility  of  the  twofold  abnormal  development,  however, 
the  normal  course  is  also  to  be  considered ;  in  this  the  pro- 
gress of  knowledge  is  followed  by  a  progress  of  the  will  and 
of  moral  power,  which  is  equal,  physically  and  mentally,  to 
the  task  of  making  ethical  everything  that  is  merely  innate 
and,  in  this  sense,  merely  natural. 

5.  The  necessity  of  manifoldncss,  or  the  princiijle  of  indi- 
vidualization in  the  moral  world.  For  a  moral  world  there 
is  needed  not  merely  a  multitude  of  natural  and  of  mental 
objects,  divided  the  one  from  the  other.  The  multitude 
might  be  a  mere  repetition  of  one  and  the  same  thing.  What 
real  value  could  there  be  in  making  more  than  once  what 
is  wholly  identical  1  With  justice  Leibnitz  laid  down  the 
principium  indiscernihilium,  i.e.  the  principle  of  the  identity 
of  the  indistinguishable.  Nothing  connected,  esj^ecially  no 
organism,  could  come  from  mere  identity ;  mere  identity 
would,  instead  of  true  union,  only  amount  to  the  atomistic 
aggregation  of  a  sand-heap.  If  every  individual  sought  to  be, 
or  were,  the  whole,  instead  of  for  the  whole  (the  outcome  of 
the  position  of  Kant  and  of  Fichte),  then  an  organic  combi- 
nation would  be  out  of  the  question  ;  there  could  only  be 
disconnectedness,  and  the  world  would  become  an  infinite 
repetition.  To  prepare  the  world  to  be  a  moral  world,  there- 
fore, it  is  essential  also  that  the  single  beings  in  the  world, 
although  relative  wholes,  be  really  distinct  from  one  another, 
not  merely  distinct  in  space  and  time,  but  capable  of  supple- 
menting one  another.  It  is  therefore  an  advance  in  ethics 
as  necessary  as  it  is  great,  v/hen  Schleiermacher  accords  to 
individuality,  or  personal  peculiarity,  an  essential,  objective, 
imperishable  significance  in  the  moral  world. 

But  if,  now,  individuality  should  be  emphasized  so  far  as  to 
leave  nothing  identical  in  the  different  individuals,  then  again 
the  consequence  would  be  precisely  the  same  as  if  an  exclusive 


ANTITHESIS  OF  LIKENESS  AND  OF  INDIVIDUALITY.  Ill 

identity  prevailed  ;  the  individuals  would  remain  disconnected, 
for  ever  flying  away  from  one  another,  repelling  one  another, 
incapable  of  entering  into  the  relation  of  mutually  giving  and 
receiving.  Thus  again  the  unity  of  the  moral  organism  would 
be  destroyed,  and  even  the  very  idea  of  morality  itself.  For 
it  would  no  longer  be  possible  to  maintain  that  morality  is 
one  and  the  same  thing  in  the  multiplicity  of  persons,  even 
on  the  assumption  that  this  one  morality  may  be  most  mani- 
fold in  form.  So  then  it  is  only  when  there  is  this  antithesis 
of  sameness  and  of  individuality  (which  is  by  no  means  a 
contradiction,  but  requires  a  co-operation  of  both),  that  ethical 
life  and  an  ethical  organism  are  possible.  The  Apostle  Paul 
has  already  taught  this  in  1  Cor.  xii.  and  xiv. 

We  can  now  pass  on  to  the  syllabus  of  the  first  part. 


^.—SYSTEM    OF    ETHICS. 

FIRST  PART.     FOUNDATION. 

§  9a.  Syllabus.      (Cf.  p.  51  sq.) 

The  First  Part  of  Ethics  treats  of  the  divine  order  of  the  world 
as  the  antecedent  condition  on  which  the  possibility  of 
morality  in  general  depends  ;  and  it  falls  into  three 
divisions.  (1)  In  creation  God  has  in  view  a  relatively 
independent  moral  world,  a  second  world  upon  the  basis 
of  the  first  or  natural  world.  (2)  The  formal  laiv  of 
the  ethical  activity  of  the  created  forces  is  to  be 
described  ;  and  (3)  the  i)ractical  end  of  this  activity — 
an  end  which  not  merely  precedes  the  creation  as  a 
thought  in  God,  but  which  is  also  innate  in  the  world 
from  the  beginning  as  the  end  which  it  is  to  attain,  and 
which  in  the  form  of  requirement  sets  the  moral  process 
on  foot.      Accordingly — 

Division  I.  Treats  of  the  order  of  the  world  in  itself  as 
established  by  God  in  creation,  irrespective 
of  the  moral  process. 

Division  II.  Treats  of  the  order  of  the  world  as  constitu- 
tionally adapted  to  a  formal  moral  process. 

Division  HI.  Treats  of  the  moral  order  of  the  world  as  the 
practical  goal  of  the  moral  process. 


§  10.  mam's  natueal  endowment.  113 


FIRST     DIVISION. 

OF  THE  OEDER  OF  THE  WORLD  ESTABLISHED  ORIGINALLY,  OR 
AT  CREATION,  AS  THE  PREREQUISITE  OF  MORALITY,  AND 
CONSIDERED  WITH  REFERENCE  TO  THE  PHYSICAL,  THE 
PSYCHICAL,  AND  THE  RATIONAL  NATURE,  AS  THESE  THREE 
ARE  PRIMARILY  CONSTITUTED  AND  CONNECTED. 

First  Section.  That  which  is  common  in  the  moral  facul- 
ties with  which  man  is  endowed. 

Second  Section.  Individuality. 

Third  Section.  The  spontaneous  working  of  the  moral 
faculties  towards  union. 

FIRST    SECTION. 

In  the  first  section,  in  three  chapters,  that  which  is  common 
in  the  moral  constitution  of  man  is  to  be  considered,  accord- 
ing to  the  above-named  three  aspects  of  his  nature,  as  Physical, 
Psychical,  and  Rational. 

CHAPTER  FIRST. 

man's  natural  or  physical  endowment  by  creation. 

§  10. 
Man,  although  destined  for  a  moral  existence,  is  first  made  by 
God  a  finite  natural  being.  But  the  moral  end  for 
which  he  is  made  is  subserved  both  by  the  fact  that  he 
is  a  natural  and  finite  being  in  general,  and  also  by  thfr 
fact  that  he  has  a  multitude  of  powers,  senses,  and 
impulses,  which  have  their  centre  in  the  oneness  of 
his  ego,  or  in  his  natural  personality.^ 

'[Literature:  Eick,  Physiologie  und  Anatomie  der  Sinnesorgane,  1864. 
Wundt,  Lehrbuch  der  Physiologie  des  Menschen,  1873,  3rd  ed.  Physiologische 
Psychologie.  Vorlesungen  ilher  die  Menschen-  und  Thierseele,  1863.  Joh, 
Muller,  Handbuch  der  Physiologie  des  Menschen.  [Elements  of  Physiology, 
translated  by  W.  Baly,  2  vols.,  Loudon  1837-42,— Te.]  J.  Ranke,  Grundziigc 
der  Physiologie  des  Menschen,  2nd  ed.  1872.     L.  F.  Helmholtz,  Die  Lehre  von 

H 


114  §  10.  man's  natural  endowment. 

1.  Finiteness  is  often  regarded  as  an  imperfection,  or  even 
as  an  evil ;  indeed,  many  see  in  it  the  source  of  wickedness  : 
for  it  constitutes,  they  say,  at  any  rate  a  deficiency,  whether  it 
be  through  matter,  or  through  the  limitation  which  it  involves. 
Ethics  teaches,  on  the  other  hand,  that  finiteness  is  to  be  con- 
sidered as  a  good  thing,  without  which  human  morality  would 
be  wholly  impossible,  and  God  alone  would  be  existent.  We 
are  finite,  not  for  the  reason  that  we  are  defective  or  connected 
with  matter  which  is  hostile  to  spirit.  Neither  inward  nor 
outward  finiteness  is  in  itself  a  defect. 

(a)  The  inivard  metaphysical  ground  of  our  finiteness  lies 
in  the  fact  that  we  do  not  have  in  ourselves  the  ground  or 
principle  of  our  existence,  that  we  are  not  self-existent, — in 
other  words,  in  the  fact  that  we  are  creatures.  Tlie  creature, 
made  Ijy  God  and  not  by  itself,  is  given  to  itself;  but  that  is 
neither  defectiveness  nor  a  cause  of  defects.  It  is  true  that 
this  involves  absolute  dependence  upon  God,  without  which 
there  would  be  nothing  except  God.  Absolute  dependence 
seems,  indeed,  to  be  not  favourable,  but  opposed,  to  morality, 
For  in  morality  the  essential  thing  is  the  positing  of  one's  self 
in  willing  and  knowing; — it  is  one's  own  production  of  the 
shape  or  form  of  his  moral  life.  But  certain  as  it  is  that 
absolute  dependence  as  such  is  not  morality,  it  no  less 
certainly  forms  the  antecedent  condition  of  morality,  and  is 
essential  in  order  to  the  possibility  of  morality.  This  is  so, 
indeed,  only  because  the  absolute  divine  causality  and  the 
absolute  dependence  of  man  do  not  exclude,  but  include,  the 
self-positing  of  the  created  being,  on  the  ground  of  his  having 
been  posited  ;  as  will  be  more  distinctly  shown  later  under  the 

den  Tonempjindungen.  [0?j  the  Sensations  of  Tone,  translated  by  A,  J.  Ellis, 
2nd  ed.,  Longmans  &  Co.,  1885. — Tr.]  Physioloyische  Optik.  Volkmann, 
Pliysiolorjische  Untersttchungen  im  Gehiete  der  Optik,  Leipzig  1863.  Ribot, 
Die  experimentdle  Psycliologie  der  Gegenviart  in  Deutschland.  [Also  English 
Ftychology,  1873,  translated  from  the  French.— Tii.]  Fechner,  Psychophysik. 
Mueller,  Zur  Grundlegung  der  Psychophysik.  Liebmann,  Analysis  der  Wirk- 
lirhkeit,  1876,  Abschn.  2,  2nd  ed.  Ulrici,  Gott  und  der  Mensch,  2nd  ed.  1874, 
Harms,  Die  Philosophie  in  ihrer  Geschichte,  1876.  Psychologic,  1874,  especially 
J).  104  sq,  Zeller,  Messung  psychischer  Vorgdnge.  Lotze,  Grundzilge  der 
Psychologie,  1881,  Mikrokosmus.  [In  English,  Microcosmus,  an  Essay  con- 
cerning Man  and  his  Relation  to  the  World,  translated  by  Elizabeth  Hamilton 
and  E.  E.  C.  Jones.  Edinburgh:  T.  &  T.  Clark,  1885.— Te.]  Further  litera- 
ture, see  above,  §  9.  3,  §  15.— Ed.] 


IXWAKD  GKOUND  OF  HUMAN  FINITEXESS.  115 

topic  of  freedom.  At  present,  only  tlio  following:  Since 
God's  creative  activity  is  of  an  ethical  character,  and  since 
He  has  made  the  world  for  morality.  He  has  designed  that  the 
creature  shall  be  a  participator  in  his  own  self-production, 
namely,  as  an  ethical  creature.  For  morality  requires 
conscious,  spontaneous  activity,  and  therefore  the  endowment 
requisite  for  it.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  this  involves^that 
just  in  order  to  have  the  dignity  of  an  ethical  being,  man 
ought  not  to  be  at  the  very  outset  all  that  he  can  become 
and  is  to  become.  And  however  high  he  may  stand  as  over 
against  the  rest  of  the  natural  creation,  yet,  in  comparison 
with  his  destination,  he  must  begin  with  a  meagre  reality, 
but  at  the  same  time  be  endued  with  an  infinitely  rich  and 
pure  possibility  of  self-development  and  self-culture.  And 
even  his  original  deficiency  brings  with  it  the  advantage  that 
he  can  as  much  as  possible  be  a  conscious  and  voluntary 
participator  in  the  work  of  his  own  self-culture  (1  Cor.  iii.  9). 
This  deficiency  is  a  seal  of  his  ethical  destination,  but  no 
defect,  although  pointing  to  original  want  of  perfection. 
Man  is  thus  confined  to  temporal  conditions,  and  is  finite  in 
respect  to  time.  But  this  apparent  deficiency,  this  gradual- 
ness  of  development,  is  favourable  to  the  moral  building  ujj 
of  our  personality.  For  now  we  ourselves  can  determine  and 
seize  every  factor  one  after  the  other  in  our  progress ;  the 
growth  can  now  be  effected  by  means  of  ever  newly-awakening 
desire  after  still  further  progress  on  the  foundation  of  that 
which  has  been  previously  made. 

Note.  —  We  have  already  had  to  insist  on  the  essential 
likeness  of  moral  goodness  in  God  and  of  morality  in  man. 
Now  by  w^ay  of  supplement  follows  their  difference.  First, 
God  alone  has  absolute  ethical  aseity,  and  it  is  only  a  copy  of 
this  which  is  found  in  the  moral  self-shaping  of  man.  Secondly, 
God  is  holy  love  perfected  eternally  ;  wdiat  in  man  can  be  only 
successive,  in  God  is  simultaneously  eternally  present.  Finally, 
although  in  man  there  is  the  fundamental  disposition  which  as 
such  wills  the  good  in  general,  yet  the  realization  of  the  good 
can  be  promoted  ^^v  him  only  in  one  part  of  the  total  work ; 
whereas  God's  good  t^.  ^  holy  will  continually  embraces  in 
providential  comprehensiveiic..  the  whole  and  every  individual 
part,  one  in  the  other.  His  good  and  gracious  will  is  compre 
heusively  directed  at  every  moment  towards  producing  and 
preserving  the  whole  moral   organism   of  the  world,  or  the 


116  §  10.    MAN'S  NATUKAL  ENDOWMENT. 

kingdom  of  God.  For  us,  on  the  contrary,  the  limitation  to 
one  field  is  even  a  condition  of  mastership  in  every  kind  of 
ethical  productiveness. 

(5)  Man,  however,  is  finite,  not  merely  inwardly  and 
naturally,  i.e.  limited  by  his  absolute  dependence  on  God  and 
by  the  necessity  of  growth.  He  is  also  limited  in  outiuard 
respects  in  a  threefold  manner :  by  his  body,  by  nature,  and 
by  the  human  race.  Only  on  the  basis  of  individual  cor- 
poreality does  personality  spring  up ;  only  through  the 
medium  of  the  body  does  the  spirit  come  to  an  existence 
which  is  capable  of  manifesting  itself  and  of  working  with 
power  in  the  world.  Nature  is  not  the  mother  of  mind ; 
mind  is  not  an  efflorescence  of  nature ;  therefore,  also,  body  is 
not  mind  or  a  potency  of  mind.  But  by  means  of  mind, 
which  has  the  power  of  life  in  itself,  matter  becomes  animated 
and  organized ;  ^  and  by  the  fact  that  mind  manifests  itself  as 
soul,  matter  becomes  body.  The  soul  upholds  the  body ;  but 
it  is  also  in  its  state  and  activity  conditioned  by  the  body. 

As  over  against  nahire,  man  is  not  merely  limited  in  time 
and  space,  but  he  is  also  originally  helpless,  in  need  of 
nature,  and  dependent  on  it  because  of  the  nature  which  he 
has  in  himself,  viz,  the  body. 

Lastly,  the  finiteness  of  man  is  shown  also  in  his  relation 
to  the  race ;  not  the  individual  is  the  man ;  others  have  what 
I  have  not :  they  are  my  limitation. 

But  this  threefold  limitation  subserves  morality  and  is  thus 
a  good ;  it  is  that  which  makes  possible  a  threefold  moral  life 
in  receptivity  and  activity.  For  first,  the  hody  is  the  organ 
of  the  mind ;  through  it  both  other  minds  and  also  what  is 
not  mental  are  yet  brought  into  relation  to  the  mind.  For 
the  body  is  the  vehicle  by  Mdiich  the  outward  world  can  work 
upon  the  mind,  and  can  be  taken  in  by  it.  But  none  the 
less  is  the  body  the  organ  by  which  the  mind  can  operate  on 
that  which  it  is  not,  whether  nature  or  mind.  In  both  these 
ways  together  it  becomes,  as  it  were,  the  abode,  the  mirror, 
and  the  visible  copy,  of  the  mind,  and  also  the  medium 
through  which  the  mind  attains  reality.  It  is  therefore  not 
a  mere  limit,  a  bound ;  it  is  also  a  bond  of  union  with  the 
outward  world ;  and  it  is  thus  capable  of  serving  as  a  means 

1  Gen.  i.  20  sq.,  24  sq.,  ii.  7. 


THE  COMMON  ENDOWMENTS  OF  MEN.  117 

whereby  the  mind  overcomes  restraints  and  liberates  itself  in 
the  exercise  of  thought  and  volition ;  it  does  not  serve  merely 
to  limit  the  mind  in  relation  to  other  things. 

Nature  outside  of  us,  moreover,  is  a  material,  which  on  the 
one  hand  is  to  be  apprehended,  on  the  other  to  be  acted  on. 
It  is  capable  of  receiving  the  seal  of  mind,  of  symbolizing  its 
ideas  in  sensible  copies,  e.g.  in  language ;  but  it  is  also  capable 
of  becoming  an  instrument  of  its  activity,  an  extension,  as  it 
were,  of  the  bodily  organ. 

Finally,  the  limitation  through  mmilcincl,  the  difference 
between  us  and  other  beings  of  our  race,  is  the  prerequisite 
of  a  social  life,  serving  botli  to  enrich  one's  own  being  and  to 
supplement  one's  work. 

2.  We  come  now  to  consider  more  particularly  tlu 
universal  or  common  endowments  of  men  as  finite  individuals. 
In  this  relation,  it  is  true,  man  is  only  the  acme  of  nature 
itself ;  but  even  as  such  he  is  something  great,  bearing  not 
obscurely  in  himself  the  seal  of  his  moral  destination.  For 
the  whole  sum  of  the  faculties,  which  inhere  in  him  as  a 
finite  being,  is  indispensable  in  order  to  an  actual  moral 
existence ;  and  only  in  such  an  existence  do  these  faculties 
attain  their  final  destination,  although  even  irrespective  of 
morality  they  are  somewhat  in  themselves.  Even  before  the 
consciousness  of  something  which  has  infinite  universal  worth 
is  awakened  or  given,  man  is  not  merely  a  multiplicity  of 
faculties,  impulses,  and  sensibilities,  but  they  are  all  central- 
ized by  the  ego  (Gen.  ii.  7  ;  1  Cor.  xv.  45).  Man  is  not 
merely  a  union  of  body  and  soul  like  the  brute  creation,  but 
a  union  of  animated  body  and  personal  soul.  And  this 
centralization  works  in  a  reflex  way  on  the  body.  The 
body  also,  on  its  part,  even  before  tlie  actual  ego  exists,  yet, 
because  united  with  a  soul  about  to  become  a  person,  is 
a  living  centre  in  the  system  of  natural  life,  and  likewise 
presents  a  real  prototype  of  the  coming  personality.  The 
human  body  is  the  specific  organ  for  the  personality,  and  therein 
essentially  different  from  brute  body  ^  (1  Cor.  xv.  45). 

The  idea  of  the  human  body,  which  lies  in  the  relation  of 
the  body  to  the  personality,  is  directed  towards  making  the 
body  always  in  one  respect  the  organ   of  the  personal  mind. 

1  Schaller,  1.0.211  sq. 


118        §10.    man's  NATURAL  ENDOWMENT.       TELEOLOGICAL 

Hence,  though  the  differences  between  man  and  other 
creatures,  e.g.  apes,  may  seem  slight  in  single  instances,  yet 
they  run  through  the  whole,  and  always  in  the  same  respect 
which  has  been  specified.  Though  the  brutes  have  eyes,  ears, 
etc.,  yet  they  hear  tones  otherwise  than  man  does ;  though 
they,  as  well  as  we,  see  pictures  or  flowers,  yet  they  do  not 
see  in  them  the  same  thing  as  we.  That  the  organs  of  man 
in  comparison  with  those  of  brutes  always  point  to  what  is 
truly  human,  is  effected  partly  by  slight  variations ;  but  just 
these  variations  show  that  the  organs  are  intended  for  a 
person  and  for  his  purposes.  This  is  illustrated,  e.g.,  by  the 
position  of  the  eyes,  the  ears,  and  the  head  ;  it  has  been  shown 
that  a  slight  variation  in  the  external  ear  is  that  which  enables 
us  to  perceive  musical  tones  as  such.  But  let  us  enter  some- 
what more  into  detail. 

The  whole  bodily  organism  of  man  contains  wonderful 
teleoloffical  contrivance.  This  is  seen  not  merely  in  what  is 
in  it,  but  also  in  the  absence  of  sucli  things  as  the  brute 
creation  brings  into  the  world  as  its  ready-made  natural  equip- 
ment. The  eye  exists  for  the  light,  the  ear  for  sound,  and  the 
lungs  for  air.  To  man  is  denied  tlie  instinct  which  makes 
other  creatures  early  mature,  but  which  also  greatly  restricts 
their  perfectibility,  and  almost  makes  needless  the  task  of 
self-perfection.  Man  is  in  each  one  of  the  single  natural  opera- 
tions of  his  organism  surpassed  by  other  creatures — in  strength 
by  some,  in  speed  or  in  keenness  of  senses  by  others.  On 
the  other  hand,  his  organism  has  a  flexibility,  an  elasticity, 
a  capacity  for  culture,  which  make  him  capable  of  an  un- 
limited development.  By  virtue  of  this  unbounded  perfecti- 
bility he  is  superior  to  them  all.  By  Bluraenbach  the  human 
race  is  designated  as  inermis,  but  tlie  obverse  side  of  the 
picture  is  given  in  Franklin's  designation  of  man  as  the 
animal  instrumcntificum.  His  elasticity  is  illustrated  especi- 
ally by  his  ability  to  live  in  all  zones,  and  to  take  possession 
of  everything,  although  this  is  not  done  without  bringing 
into  play  the  flexible  adaptability  or  accommodation  which 
he  assumes,  for  example,  in  the  differences  of  the  races,  in 
order  to  maintain  himself.  He  alone  is  intended  to  walk 
upright,  as  is  shown  by  the  structure  of  the  organs  of 
locomotion  and  the  position  of  the  organs  of  the  senses. 


CONSTRUCTION  OF  THE  BODY,  THE  HAND.  THE  VOICE.      119 

Especially  worthy  of  mention  is  the  ingenious  construction 
of  the  hand.  The  hand  is  the  member  in  which  whole 
ethical  creations  have  set  up  their  abode,  e.g.  the  arts  and 
industries  ;  yes,  it  is  the  member  which  from  the  beginning 
helps  not  merely  to  symbolize,  but  also  to  produce,  to 
mediate,  all  revelation  of  inner  morality, — as  is  indicated  by 
the  etymology  of  the  word  "  Handeln  "  [Eng.  to  act].  In  the 
hand  are  united  the  ability  to  feel  and  the  ability  to  work.^ 

The  senses  may  be  called  the  susceptibility  of  the  soul 
for  the  outward  world  and  its  wealth.  Among  the  various 
theories  of  perception,  that,  indeed,  has  the  least  in  its  favour 
which  regards  the  soul  as  a  blank  tablet  to  be  written  on 
by  the  senses.  Eather  in  the  thinking  mind  is  inborn  an 
essential  reference  to  everything  which  exists,  since  every- 
thing existent  is  itself  also  thought,  namely,  realized  thought. 
The  mind  has  from  creation  the  capacity  to  know  about 
existing  things,  but  yet  it  is  not  furnished  with  innate  ideas, 
nor  with  an  innate  knowledge  of  single  things,  which  are 
undergoing  continual  flux  and  change.  On  the  other  hand, 
when  the  senses  are  stirred  b}^  the  continually-present  out- 
ward world,  it  comes  to  pass  that,  as  by  a  stroke  of  magic, 
the  image  of  surrounding  things  is  produced  by  the  sense- 
impressions,  and  is  allured  forth  from  the  soul,  accompanied 
with  the  consciousness  that  we  have  to  do  not  merely  with 
subjective  conceptions,  but  with  intuitions  of  reality,  which 
present  material  for  action. 

The  voice,  furthermore,  which  is  given  to  the  higher 
beings,  becomes  in  man  the  gift  of  speech.  This  gift  is  of 
the  highest  importance  with  reference  to  the  position  of  man 
in  the  world,  and  it  reacts  to  enhance  the  value  of  the 
senses.  By  means  of  speech,  the  ear,  the  most  intellectual 
of  the  senses,  first  attains  its  higher  significance ;  by  means 
of  speech,  also,  an  exchange  between  the  different  senses 
takes  place,  a  translation,  as  it  were,  from  the  one  into  the 
other.  The  word,  which  is  properly  for  the  ear,  becomes 
writing  by  means  of  the  hand,  and  is  made  accessible  to  the 
eye,  for  which  the  word  itself  is  insufficient.     The  writing 

'  The  Bridgetvater  Treatises  contain  an  admirable  dissertation  on  the 
ingenious  teleological  construction  of  the  hand.  Of.  also  Giebel,  Die  mensch- 
liche  Hand,  in  the  Zeitschr./ur  die  cjesammte  Naturwissenschaft,  vol.  xli.  1873. 


120  §  10.  man's  natural  endowment. 

is  again  translated  for  the  ear  by  means  of  speech.  Every- 
thing seen  can  be  clothed  in  words,  and  thus  be  represented 
to  the  ear,  in  order  to  be  an  object  for  the  mind,  even 
when  the  immediate  vision  is  inadequate  to  make  it  such. 
Thus  it  comes  to  pass  by  means  of  speech,  which  is,  as  it 
were,  the  universal  mental  medium  of  exchange,  that  the 
various  senses  take  the  place  of  one  another ;  one  under- 
takes the  office  of  another,  as,  e.g.,  even  the  blind  can  read  by 
the  sense  of  touch,  and  the  deaf  hear  by  the  vicarious  sense  of 
vision,  the  prerequisite  for  all  this  being  the  existence  of  a 
general  indifferent  medium  of  exchange  and  of  understanding. 

By  speech  nature  is,  to  the  widest  extent,  mediately  and 
immediately  used  for  the  world  of  thought  and  appropriated 
by  the  mind ;  from  the  fleeting  word  of  the  tongue,  which 
wondrously  weaves  out  of  air  a  body  for  thought,  and  presents 
it  for  the  moment  an  animate  object,  up  to  the  written 
characters,  in  which  thought  lies  rigid  and  enchained,  but 
also  acquires  permanent  fixedness,  so  that,  being  capable  of  a 
reawakening  at  any  time,  it  almost  divests  itself  of  transi- 
toriness,  and  can  remain  present  for  distant  times ;  from 
this  again  up  to  the  invention  of  the  press,  which  conquers 
not  only  the  transitoriness  of  time,  but  also  of  space,  by 
investing  with  a  certain  omnipresence  and  perpetuity  the 
thought  and  word  which  were  uttered  at  one  place  and  in  one 
time,  and  by  being  able  to  collect  together  in  every  place  the 
most  important  tilings  that  have  happened  scattered  through 
all  places  and  all  times.  The  domain  of  speech  is  so  great, 
indeed,  because  language  is  not  merely  a  natural  gift,  but  also 
a  moral  product ;  nevertheless,  everything  in  it  is  only  the 
evolution  and  the  use  of  the  endowments  and  faculties 
which  are  inborn  and  distinctively  human. 

Finally,  let  us  glance  at  the  natural  endowment  of  man 
for  self  -  preservation  and  reproduction.  All  living  beings 
have  the  power  of  self-preservation,  by  which  they  keep  their 
identity  amidst  all  change  of  matter — a  unity  which  therefore 
is  something  else  than  matter.  The  preservation  of  things  is 
essentially  involved  in  the  creative  will.  But  preservation 
is  not  possible  without  allowing  a  causality  to  them  (Gen.  i. 
12,  22,  28).  The  first  function  of  their  causality  is  self- 
preservation,  or  self-reproduction.     This  takes  place,  first,  by 


THE  FACULTY  OF  SELF-PKESERVATION.  121 

continual  assimilation  of  material,  which  repairs  what  is  con- 
sumed, and  incorporates  with  the  organism  and  its  vital 
process  the  matter  which  outside  of  this  organism  is  inani- 
mate. But  the  living  creature  also  preserves  itself  as  a 
species,  which  can  be  undying  amid  the  change  of  individuals ; 
the  individuals  are  here  the  organs  of  the  species  which 
maintains  and  propagates  itself  through  them.  In  man  the 
capacity  for  this  self-reproduction  attains  moral  significance 
through  the  will,  and  is  the  foundation  of  important  depart- 
ments of  morals. 

In  all  these  attributes,  gifts,  and  functions  comprised  in 
the  divine  idea  of  man,  in  their  normal  character  or  soundness 
and  vigour,  and  again  in  the  harmonious  vitality  and  beauty  of 
this  organism,  are  to  be  seen  so  many  good  things,  which 
really  deserve  this  name,  and  are  in  the  sight  of  God  them- 
selves of  worth  (Gen.  i.  31).  There  is  something  sacred  in 
them;  and  wantonness  which  injures  them  is  an  encroach- 
ment on  God's  order ;  hence  they  are  included  in  the  moral 
world.  The  guarding  of  these  good  gifts,  their  increase  and 
development,  is  a  part  of  the  ethical  work  itself;  it  is 
included  in  the  process  of  reducing  the  world  to  moral  order. 
It  is  true  that  the  care  and  culture  of  them  may  possibly  be 
destitute  of  the  higher,  central,  ethical  meaning,  and  may 
perhaps  treat  them  not  as  means  in  furtherance  of  the  highest 
general  end.  Nevertheless  they  also  are  comprehended  under 
the  general  end  as  something  to  be  cared  for.  Even  if 
there  is  as  yet  no  moral  disposition  to  protect  their  normal 
sacred  order  against  caprice  and  disturbance,  yet  they  already 
form  a  part  of  what  morality  has  to  deal  with.  Hence  also 
even  in  this  lowest  sphere  there  is  a  physical  analogue  of 
virtue,  namely,  that  efficiency  of  the  bodily  organism  which  is  to 
be  gained  and  guarded  ;  and  in  this  self-preservation  of  normal 
nature  the  creative  will  is  affirmed  and  confirmed  by  the 
human  will ;  and  the  latter  is  in  the  exercise  of  this  function 
good  in  its  kind,  although  not  yet  possessed  of  moral  character. 

Note. — From  the  high  position  we  must  give  to  nature  and 
corporeality,  it  cannot  be  inferred  that  the  importance  of  the 
ethical  process  in  the  world's  history  consists  in  general,  as 
Eothe  makes  it,  in  the  subjection  of  matter,  or  in  the  production 
of  spirit,  as  the  union  of  the  real  and  the  ideal.    The  final  cause 


122  §  11.  man's  psychical  constitution. 

of  the  world  is  rather  the  production  of  love,  which,  however, 
needs  nature  in  order  to  its ,  expression  and  dissemination : 
Love,  in  its  treatment  of  nature,  affirms  the  laws  of  the  first 
creation,  takes  them  up  into  its  will,  and  treats  all  things 
according  to  their  several  kinds,  but  for  its  own  end.  The 
ethical  process  must  indeed  adapt  itself  to  the  immanent 
laws  of  the  normal  movement  of  life  in  nature,  but  it  does  so 
only  so  far  that  thereby  the  manner  is  determined  in  which 
love,  which  fixes  the  goal  and  directs  the  process,  shall  attain  its 
own  goal. 


CHAPTEE  SECOND. 

THE  psychical  ELEMENT  IN  MAN'S  MOKAL  CONSTITUTION, 
IKRESPECTIVE  AS  YET  OF  REASON.       ..  . 

§   11. 

The  natural  personality  is  a  unity  which  persists  in  the  midst 
of  the  alterations  of  the  bodily  organism,  and  remains 
identical  with  itself  by  virtue  of  the  soul.  The  soul  is 
fitted  for  morality  by  its  so-called  fundamental  faculties 
in  general  ;  but  in  particular  by  the  capacity  which 
these  faculties  have  of  being  determined  by  one  another ; 
and  further,  by  the  soul's  capacity  of  existing  both  as  an 
agent,  having  the  power  to  act,  and  as  a  state,  involving 
the  possibility  of  characUr. 

1.  Erom  the  Physical  we  pass  to  the  Psychical.  Since  it 
is  necessary  to  assume  that  the  body  and  the  soul  are  two 
things  (§  9),  but  it  is  not  sufficient  to  assume  a  mere  dualism, 
the  question  arises,  how  the  connection  of  body  and  soul  is 
ensured.  The  middle  term,  essential  on  the  side  of  matter, 
is  its  susceptibility  for  force,  life,  soul,  etc.  Matter,  therefore, 
is  not  merely  that  which  is  inert,  at  rest,  impenetrable ;  it  is 
also  that  which  is  susceptible  of  force,  or  is  the  power  of 
receiving  life,  soul,  etc. ;  and  by  its  susceptibility  it  points  to 
the  higher  thing  by  which  the  susceptibility  is  to  be  satisfied, 
and  awaits  it  as  the  determining  power.  And  so  we  see  how, 
from  the  lowest  stages  where  life  and  force  seem  to  be  still 
overpowered  by  matter,   nature    rises    to    ever   freer,  higher 


THE  CONSCIOUSNESS  OF  IDENTITY.  123 

forms, — to  plants,  which  ah'eady  appropriate  matter  to  them- 
selves and  elaborate  it  for  their  growth,  and  from  plants  on  to 
animal  life.  Though  the  animal  soul  has  more  ability  to 
govern  the  body,  locomotio,  still  the  brute  is  not  able  to  con- 
trast the  soul  with  the  body.  His  soul  has,  as  the  object  of 
its  perception  and  desire,  his  body  and  its  affections.  No  higher 
stage  in  nature  is  reached  till  the  ideal  principle  in  it  has 
come  to  such  strength  that  it  can  set  itself  over  against  every- 
thing which  is  not  itself.  But  the  soul  can  do  this  only  by 
being  first  of  all  something  by  and  of  itself,  by  being  able  to 
set  itself  over  against  itself  ;  without  this  it  could  not  oppose 
other  things  to  itself.  The  product  of  this  act  is  the  ego.  If 
self-consciousness  exists,  then  there  is  given  a  fixed  point 
which  in  the  change  of  things  and  of  perceptions  remains  the 
same.  Thereby  man,  instead  of  being  lost  in  the  outside 
world,  can  rescue  himself  from  its  current. 

By  this  consciousness  of  identity,  now,  there  is  set  up,  as  it 
were,  a  fixed  mirror  in  which  the  changing  multiplicity  of 
things  reflects  itself,  and  is  even  brought  together  as  in  a  per- 
manent point  of  union.  In  this  way  consciousness,  which  can 
take  in  all  possible  things,  acquires  the  character  of  univer- 
sality, and,  as  a  susceptibility  for  everything  existent  and  per- 
ceptible, stretches  out  beyond  the  individual  ego  and  becomes 
consciousness  of  the  world.  And  the  development  of  this 
universal  side  of  the  ego  is  of  importance  in  relation  to  the 
will  and  its  freedom  of  choice :  by  virtue  of  the  fact  that  the 
soul,  as  ego,  has  a  universal  character,  containing  in  itself  in- 
finitely numerous  possibilities  of  volitions,  it  can  rescue  itself 
from  the  sensations  and  impulses,  can  draw  back  from  their 
immediate  power  into  its  own  universal  being,  can  set  them 
over  against  itself,  check  them,  deny  them,  or  will  something 
different  from  that  to  which  they  may  impel. 

2.  With  the  ego  is  connected  the  consideration  of  the 
further  psychical  character  of  man.  The  one  soul,  as  human 
or  as  ego,  has  three  forms  of  existeoice,  called  also  fundamental 
faculties  ;  they  are  sensibility,  cognition,  will.  The  details 
belong  to  the  province  of  psychology ;  in  considering  man's 
ethical  constitution  we  are  concerned  chiefly  with  the  capacity 
of  each  of  the  three  to  be  determined  by  the  others,  and  espe- 
cially of  them  all  to  be  determined  by  the  will.     Feeling,  will. 


124  §  11.  man's  psychical  constitution. 

cognition  are  indeed  not  absolutely  separated  from  one  another, 
but  rather  are  from  the  beginning  comprehended  by  the 
natural  personality  as  their  centre  of  unity.  Yet  they  are  not 
on  that  account  one  and  the  same ;  they  are  at  first  even  rela- 
tively separable ;  they  may  be  unequal  in  their  development, 
they  may  even  oppose  one  another.  Perfect  interpenetration 
or  oneness  is  what  they  can  and  should  attain  by  a  process  of 
moulding  one  another  ;  and  this  is  a  work  which  morality  has 
to  do,  for  which  work  indeed  a  rule  is  requisite  that  shall  fix 
the  manner  in  which  this  reciprocal  moulding  is  to  be  effected. 
They  are  also  not  perfect  each  by  itself  at  the  outset,  but  can 
become  so  only  in  connection  with  one  another,  by  mutual  in- 
fluence and  determination.  Thereby  the  original  union,  which 
is  at  first,  as  it  were,  only  prefigurative,  typical,  and  superficial, 
is  to  become  affirmed  and  established  as  an  intensive,  living 
union  through  the  will.  Hence,  under  this  aspect,  we  consider 
these  three — sensibility,  cognition,  will — up  to  the  point  where 
they  are  directed  towards  the  infinite.  In  its  coming  forth 
from  itself  in  order  to  exercise  itself,  the  soul  is  will ;  in 
taking  an  outward  thing  into  its  inmost  self,  it  is  cognitive  ;  in 
the  mean  between  these  two  opposite  functions,  but  at  the 
same  time  connecting  them,  are  i\\e  feelings.  "We  here  some- 
what anticipate  the  doctrine  of  the  moral  process  (Div.  II.),  in 
order  to  take  a  survey  of  the  psychical  traits  which  make  the 
moral  process  possible. 

3.  The  Feelings. — Even  in  the  brute  the  soul  has  a  sort 
of  selfhood  ;  but  this  is  a  sense  of  having  such  and  such 
an  organism — a  sense  of  life.  The  state  of  the  organism  is 
reflected  into  the  sentient  soul  of  the  brute,  but  this  soul  does 
not  2^osscss  itself  in  its  selfhood  ;  man  does,  however.  And  so 
his  selfhood  comes  to  be  of  a  personal  sort — feeling  in  the 
narrower  sense ;  it  is  not  mere  sensation,  and  also  not  mere 
immediate  feeling,  but  the  perception  that  the  feeling  of  the 
physical  and  mental  condition  is  his  own.  This  is  in  the 
first  place  a  feeling  of  self,  in  which  that  which  is  felt  and  that 
which  feels  are  one  and  the  same  subject.  But  the  feeling 
can  also  have  something  else  than  the  ego  for  its  object,  though, 
to  be  sure,  only  so  far  forth  as  the  ego  is  inwardly  affected 
or  moved  by  it.  So  far  forth  as  this  other  object  can  be  an 
object  of  thought,  we  call  the  feeling  of  this  other  thing  an 


THE  FEELINGS.  125 

intellectual  feeling,  directed  towards  truth.  Although  as  yet 
the  modification  of  the  ego  by  the  object  is  the  predominant 
thing  in  what  takes  place, — for  it  is  feeling, — yet  this  feeling 
forms  the  transition  to  objective  conception  and  thought. 

The  second  thing  is  the  praetical  feeling  of  the  value  of  the 
object,  as  an  object  of  the  will — not  merely  of  its  value  to  the 
individual  ego ;  for  the  practical  feeling  can  also  rightly 
express  a  determination  of  general  objective  value ;  the 
feeling  appealed  to  by  the  value  of  the  object  has  likewise 
a  universal  side  to  it.  That  which  is  agreeable  to  the 
practical  feeling  of  the  soul  becomes  an  object  of  pleasure 
and  desire  ;  that  which  is  repulsive  to  this  feeling  is  what 
excites  displeasure,  is  an  object  of  repugnance  or  abhorrence. 
If  the  feeling  is  of  a  sensuous  sort,  but  joined  with  imimlse, 
while  knowledge  or  clear  thought  still  remain  in  the  back- 
ground, there  arises  appetency.  The  practical  feeling  can  be 
directed  towards  anything  whatever  which  can  have  value 
for  a  person, — towards  happiness  and  its  advantages,  towards 
beauty,  but  also  towards  truth  so  far  as  it  is  regarded  as  a 
valuable  good,  and  towards  moral  good  properly  so  called. 

Although  this  judgment  of  value  can  be  expressed  in  pure 
objective  thought,  or  conception,  by  which  the  valuable  object 
becomes  an  end,  yet  the  seat  of  the  apperception  of  worth  is 
in  the  feeling.  This  feeling  is  the  perception  of  the  pre- 
arranged harmony  between  the  object  and  the  person's  own 
nature,  i.e.  the  perception  of  the  enhancement  of  his  own 
being  by  means  of  this  object.  Also  this  feeling  of  value 
cannot  cease  when  the  valuable  thing  becomes  an  object  of 
thought  or  choice  ;  but  it  runs  all  through  these  as  an  accom- 
paniment, and  lends  to  them  both  their  intensity.  The 
thought,  into  which  the  valuable  object  is  taken  up  as  an 
idea,  secures  clearness  and  permanence,  and  guards  the  feeling 
itself  from  relapsing  into  merely  passive  sensation.  But  the 
practical  feeling  is  directed  primarily  towards  the  will.  The 
feeling,  laid  hold  of  by  the  value  of  the  object,  impels  the 
will  to  become  practically  united  with  the  object ;  and  inas- 
much as  thus  the  feeling  becomes  a  soul  for  the  will,  it  is 
called  incitement  [Tricbfcder],  whereas  thought,  in  so  far  as  it 
would  move  or  determine  the  will,  is  called  ground  or  reason 
[Beweggrund],     But  yet  the  thought,  or  reason,  becomes  an 


126  §  11.  .man's  psychical  constitution. 

actually  moving  force  only  by  passing  through  the  feelings, 
that  is,  by  becoming  likewise  an  incitement ;  and  this  union 
of  reason  and  incitement  may  be  called  motive.  The  feelings 
can  also  determine  the  loill  immediately,  without  first  passing 
through  the  medium  of  thought,  that  is,  determine  it  uncon- 
sciously as  in  ccp-pdency ;  but  thought  cannot  conversely 
determine  the  will  without  the  feelings.  The  unconscious 
incitement  is  merely  the  union  of  sensation  and  impulse 
\^Tricb\  that  is,  appetency. 

By  flowing  out  in  thought  and  will,  feeling  does  not  lose 
itself;  the  soul  always  returns  into  itself,  into  its  inmost  self, 
or  feeling, — into  the  simple,  primary  totality  of  the  mind. 
But  it  is  only  by  means  of  will  and  thought  that  feeling 
becomes  morally  educated  feeling, — a  fact  of  the  highest  im- 
portance, e.g.  in  the  matter  of  piety.  It  is  frequently  thought 
that  one  has  no  control  over  his  feelings,  that  they  cannot  be 
determined  by  the  will ;  they  even  seem  to  have  worth  only 
so  far  as  they  are  free  natural  feelings.  But  from  an  ethical 
point  of  view  it  must  be  insisted  on,  that  even  feeling  is  an 
object  of  education,  that  there  is  an  educated  moral  feeling. 
The  training  is  accomplished,  to  be  sure,  not  directly  in  a 
positive  way  ;  yet  it  is  not  merely  negatively  that  one  can 
influence  the  sensibilities,  or  repress  them,  instead  of  yielding, 
e.g.,  to  one's  moods ;  the  sensibilities  can  also  be  positively, 
at  least  indirectly,  educated,  by  the  will  and  cognition 
familiarizing  themselves  with  ideal  realms,  in  which  the 
feelings  also  are  interested.  And  as  feeling  can  be  excited 
and  fixed  by  the  objects  of  cognition  and  will,  so  too  these 
can  determine  the  feeling  by  the  state  of  being  which  they 
must  attain  (see  below). 

4.  Cognition  or  Consciousness. — In  the  sensation  and  per- 
ception of  an  outward  object,  the  soul  is  primarily  determined 
only  by  the  senses  ;  this  is  therefore  passive  cognition.  But 
yet  even  this  comes  to  pass  only  by  means  of  a  reaction  of 
the  cognitive  function  against  mere  passiveness,  that  is,  by 
means  of  activity ;  and  the  more,  now,  the  consciousness  is 
determined  by  the  will,  which  on  its  part  carries  in  itself  a 
feeling  of  the  worth  of  things, — i.e.  the  more  cognition  is 
made,  in  the  wider  sense,  ethical, — so  much  the  more  is  a 
progress  in    cognition  at  once  manifest.      Consciousness  thus 


THE  COGNITIVE  FACULTY.  127 

becomes  freed  from  passiveness,  from  being  merely  given  up 
to  the  sense  -  perception ;  consciousness  comes  to  be  actively 
passive,  i.e.  to  will  to  be  determined  by  an  object,  c.(j.  in 
attention  ;  and  this  alone  is  receptivity  which  is  living — not 
merely  immediate,  but  determined  by  the  will.  The  will, 
directed  towards  the  consciousness  as  sense-perception,  pro- 
jects out  of  itself  the  object  of  the  sensuous  impression,  or 
more  strictly,  the  image  or  conception  of  it,  puts  this  before 
itself  of  its  ovM  accord,  and  directing  itself  towards  this  fixed 
conception,  analyses  it,  according  to  its  characteristics,  in  the 
exercise  of  judgment,  but  brings  these  characteristics  again 
into  relation  to  an  underlying  unity,  embraces  them  in  a 
generic  notion,  and  appropriates  the  object  to  itself,  or  com- 
prehends it.     Thus  consciousness  is  thinJdng  consciousness. 

To  the  world  of  conceptions,  in  which  the  will  is  already 
active  as  a  plastic  and  creative  will,  although  in  the  character 
of  consciousness,  is  next  joined  the  cognitive  activity  in  the 
form  of  imagination  and  fancy.  This  activity  freely  uses 
these  conceptions  and  perceptions  as  its  own  material,  and 
freely  combines  their  objects.  Here  the  idea  of  heauty  finds  its 
domain.  The  forms  thus  produced  are  primarily  only  inward, 
without  objective  independent  existence — affections  of  the 
conceiving  soul  itself,  and  not  disengaged  from  it  till  the  will 
comes  in  more  powerfully,  and,  being  seized  by  artistic  feeling, 
gives  to  the  pictures  of  fancy  an  objective  outward  existence. 

But  when  now  the  plastic  will,  which  unites  with  con- 
sciousness, and  causes  it  to  create  ideals,  is  animated,  not 
merely  by  the  idea  of  beauty,  but  by  that  of  truth,  then  the 
shaping  and  creating  of  ideals  takes  place  beyond  the  world  of 
forms  and  of  art  in  the  sphere  of  independent  thought.  The 
highest  stage  of  this  independent  thought  is  the  cognition  of 
universal  truth,  the  thought  of  that  which  is  a  priori  necessary. 
It  is  comprehension  no  longer  in  a  mere  empirical  sense,  but 
in  a  higher  sense,  to  which  belongs  not  merely  cognition  of 
the  What,  and  of  actual  existence,  or  the  That,  but  also  the 
cognition  of  the  Why.  It  is  not  merely  perception  and  notion, 
but  also  the  grounds  for  both.  Thus  we  have  the  three 
categories  of  reality,  possibility,  and  necessity.  Thinking  which 
is  shaped  by  the  will,  or  by  personality,  is  the  intellectual 
activity  of  the  mind.     The  intellect  is  neither  merely  passive 


128  §  11.  man's  psychical  constitution. 

nor  merely  the  play  of  consciousness,  as  imagination  may  be  ; 
it  receives  its  direction  from  the  love  of  truth,  from  the 
choice  of  truth ;  but  it  must  follow  this  direction  according 
to  its  own  law,  the  necessary  law  of  thought. 

Finally,  when  cognition  is  occupied  with  what  has  value 
for  the  will,  then  we  have  practical,  purposing  cognition.  In 
its  purity  and  power  it  is  essentially  conditioned  by  the 
purity  of  the  practical  will,  and  even  of  the  feelings ;  for  all 
volition,  even  that  directed  towards  cognition,  is  animated  by 
the  feeling  of  the  worth  of  the  object  of  volition. 

5.  Conversely,  however,  the  loill  is  more  and  more  edu- 
cated, and  is  raised  to  higher  degrees,  both  by  cognition 
(consciousness  and  self-consciousness)  and  by  the  sensibilities. 
For  impulse  is  characterized  by  blindness  and  want  of  freedom, 
because  the  person  who  has  it  cannot  as  yet  distinguish  it 
from  himself,  so  that  he  is  impelled  by  the  impulse,  and  even 
continues  so  absorbed  that  he  has  come  to  be  only,  as  it  were, 
a  living  impulse,  but  does  not  impel  himself,  does  not  will. 
But  while  this  is  so,  yet,  on  the  other  hand,  as  soon  as  the  ego,  or 
the  recognition  of  self,  arises,  then  the  distinguishing  between 
the  person  and  the  impulse  can  also  begin ;  and  instead  of 
being  overpowered  by  the  impulse,  the  personality  becomes 
able  to  set  itself  up  over  against  the  impulse,  so  that  the  ego 
can  will  or  not,  can  sustain  a  voluntary  relation  to  it. 

But  the  more  the  cognition  becomes  enriched  in  its  contents, 
and  is  accompanied  by  the  feelings  in  their  attribution  of 
worth  to  the  objects  cognized,  and  by  the  consciousness  of 
these  objects  as  an  end,  so  much  the  more  is  the  will  able  to 
make  progress  from  being  mere  caprice  to  being  an  intelligent 
will  with  a  fixed  tendency ;  so  much  the  more  does  the  culture 
of  the  will  flourish.  More  particularly,  the  progress  is  accom- 
plished thus  :  The  person  by  his  own  act,  upon  receiving  an 
impulse  from  the  self-consciousness  which  holds  the  object 
before  him,  and  from  the  feelings  which  are  stirred  by  the 
object,  opens  [Germ,  ersehliesst]  himself  to  this  object,  and 
allows  himself  to  be  determined  to  lay  hold  of  it.  This  is 
resolution  [Germ.  EntscUiessung ,  literally,  unlocking,  opening]. 
It  includes,  in  the  first  place,  a  judgment  of  the  voluntary 
agent  concerning  the  object  and  its  relation  to  the  agent.  In 
the  second  place,  there  is  in  a  resolution,  although  it  moves  as 


DEFINITION  OF  ACTION.  129 

yet  in  a  purely  interior  sphere,  nevertheless  a  reference  to  the 
outward  world,  to  action  in  the  world,  to  a  determination  of 
it  by  means  of  the  mind.  With  the  thought  which  is  to  be 
realized  the  will  joins  itself  in  the  resolve,  in  order  to  make 
itself  and  its  organism  a  means  toivards  the  end,  or  in  order 
to  lend  to  thought  the  power  of  realization,  whereby  it  can 
become  a  cause.  For  the  thovglit  which  vjills  to  become 
causality  is  called  end  [purpose,  Germ.  Zuxchl.  So  much 
concerning  the  so-called  powers  of  the  soul  as  conditions  of 
morality,  but  as  yet  apart  from  the  apprehension  of  the 
infinite.^ 

6.  Action. — These  faculties,  however,  are  all  intended  for 
activity ;  and  in  particular,  the  blending  of  them  together, 
wdiich  has  been  considered,  does  not  take  place  of  itself,  but 
through  acts  of  the  person,  by  his  action,  in  tlie  broader  sense 
of  the  term.  iVristotle  likens  action  to  the  logical  relation  of 
reason  and  consequence,  and  to  the  ontological  relation  of  the 
cause  and  the  effect  of  a  principle.  Yet  the  principle  from 
which  the  action  emanates,  as  consequence  or  effect,  is,  as 
Aristotle  sees,  of  a  different  sort  from  the  principle  of  logical 
thought,  or  from  the  principles  of  things  in  nature.  For,  he 
says,  in  the  case  of  both  these  the  consequence  or  effect  pro- 
ceeds from  its  ground  or  cause  necessarily ;  whereas  that 
ground  which  becomes  the  cause  of  action  does  not  produce 
this  effect  necessarily,  but  is  a  ground  which  contains  more 
than  one  possibility.  Man  in  respect  to  action  is  cip-x}]  Kvpia  ; 
and  that  is  the  basis  of  the  imputation  that  strictly  he  might 
act  otherwise  than  he  does.  Eothe  designates  action  as  the 
function  of  the  human  personality  as  such.^  This  holds  true 
if  action  is  taken  in  the  widest  sense,  according  to  which 
every  function  of  the  human  person  when  awake  is  action. 
Action  is  to  be  distinguished  from  the  mere  hapi^emng  of 
something  through  the  participation  of  the  will  and  the  con- 

^  [Gei-man  :  "  noch  abgeselien  von  dem  Vernehmen  des  Unendlichen."  There 
is  here  an  allusion  to  the  etymology  of  "  Vernuvft''''  (reason),  it  being  derived 
from  Vernehmen,  to  apprehend,  perceive  ;  reason  being  regarded  predominantly 
as  a  perceptive  faculty,  perceptive  of  the  higher,  infinite  objects  of  thought, 
especially  God,  necessary  truth,  and  eternal  morality.  Cf.  the  heading  of  this 
chapter,  and  the  next  chapter,  where  this  conception  of  the  reason  is  developed. 
— Tr.] 

2  Ed.  1,  i.  §  194  [ed.  2,  ii.  §  222]. 

I 


130  §  11.  man's  psychical  constitution. 

sciousness,  that  is,  of  the  personality.  But  the  powers  of  the 
soul  do  not  work  like  the  mere  forces  of  nature ;  it  is  not  the 
faculties  of  the  soul  which  act,  but  the  person  acts  by  means 
of  the  faculties,  entering  into  space  and  time  out  of  his  own 
interior  being. 

Action  is  distinguished,  not  only  from  occurrences,  and 
from  the  working  of  mere  natural  forces,  but  also  from  all 
other  conceivable  psychical  emotions,  blind  impulses,  or  sensa- 
tions, in  which  the  personality  does  not  co-operate  by  way  of 
assenting  or  determining,  and  so  does  not  form  a  constituent 
part.  Inasmuch  as  personality  is  the  union  of  self-conscious- 
ness and  will,  and  in  every  human  act  the  personality  must 
be  present,  it  follows  that  every  act  must  involve  consciousness 
and  will,  though  with  the  greatest  variety  of  degree  of  parti- 
cipation. But  as  only  persons,  and  not  brutes,  can  act,  so 
conversely  every  act  of  a  person  is  of  a  moral  sort  in  the 
equivocal  sense,  i.e.  normally  moral  or  not.  But  from  action 
in  the  wider  sense,  with  which  the  ego  has  some  association, 
we  must  distinguish  action  in  the  narrower  sense.  For  although 
we  speak  of  acts  of  consciousness,  nay,  though  the  mind  is  a 
reality  only  by  virtue  of  acts,  which  cannot  take  place  without 
the  will,  yet  acts  in  the  narrower  sense  are  only  those  acts 
of  the  will  which  have  a  deed  as  their  goal,  and  which  the 
acts  of  consciousness  or  the  emotions  of  the  sensibilities  sub- 
serve only  as  means ;  but  not  those  acts  in  relation  to  which 
the  will  constitutes  only  a  means  of  cognition,  and  cognition 
is  the  goal.  These  acts  of  the  will  wdiich  aim  at  deeds  may, 
with  Fichte,  be  called  Tlmtlictndlungcn  [deed-acts],  and  they 
are  of  the  most  immediate  importance  with  reference  to  ethics. 

In  a  complete  act,  feeling,  cognition,  and  volition  work 
together ;  but  the  important  point  is  to  discern  how  they 
work — to  analyse  the  act.  The  first  factor  is  the  practiced 
feeling,  which  relates  to  the  worth  of  the  thing  which  may 
become  an  object  of  the  will ;  it  is  the  feeling  which  estimates 
worth.  Yet  this  feeling  of  pleasure  or  displeasure  may  pos- 
sibly only  advance  as  far  as  appetency,  which  carries  the  will 
along  with  it ;  in  that  case  there  is  as  yet  no  freedom,  because 
there  is  no  clearness  of  consciousness.  But  the  course  may 
also  normally  proceed  further  ;  and  then,  secondly,  the  practical 
feeling  of  the  worth  or  worthlessness  of  the  object  takes  shape 


FEELING,  DESIKE,  RESOLUTION.  131 

in  the  consciousness,  which  is  active  in  the  character  of  will, 
i.e.  which  forms  concepts  for  the  will — forms  ends.  For  an 
end  is  a  concept  which  is  addressed  to  the  will,  and  which 
presupposes  the  valuation  given  in  the  practical  feeling.  But 
starting  with  the  consciousness  of  the  end,  the  will  passes 
through  several  other  stages  before  reaching  the  voluntary  act 
[Thatliandlungi,  viz.  the  stages  of  desire,  of  resolve  with 
2nirpose,  and  finally  of  the  deed.  For,  thirdly,  the  end  recom- 
mended by  the  feeling  of  worth  and  fixed  by  the  consciousness 
awakens  in  the  ego  a  desire  for  the  good  which  is  conceived. 
Desire  is  not  mere  appetency,  but  it  is  also  not  action ;  in 
desire  the  will  only  opens  itself  to  the  alluring  power  of  the 
good,  or  the  end,  which  is  conceived,  and  which  is  ideally 
present.  It  is,  indeed,  not  merely  passive,  and  also  not  yet 
productive,  but  receptive,  ideally  conceptive,  in  relation  to  the 
object,  whether  good  or  evil.^ 

When,  now,  the  will  inwardly  combines  with  the  end  which 
is  conceived,  and  which  recommends  itself  as  worthy  of 
realization, — when  the  will  so  surrenders  itself  to  the  end  as  to 
make  itself  the  means  of  accomplishing  it,  this  is  resolution,  the 
result  of  which  is  'pur'posc,  resting  on  the  incitement  that  has 
grown  out  of  the  valuation  which  the  practical  feeling  and  the 
understanding  have  exercised.  A  resolve  is  no  longer  a 
simple  desire  or  longing,  mingled  with  involuntariness,  but  it 
is  a  higher,  an  inward  volition,  which  involves  another  sub- 
sequent volition,  namely,  a  volition  which  is  to  realize  the 
end,  a  volition  of  the  deed.  This  is  a  volition  of  a  volition,  a 
volition  in  the  second  degree.  The  resolve  is  the  volition  of 
a  volition  which  shall  not  remain  inward,  but  shall  be  so 
vigorous  and  decided  that  the  will  becomes  a  cause,  and 
realizes  the  end.  The  resolution  forms  a  fixed  point  in  the 
present,  a  conclusion  of  the  wavering,  scattered  functions  of 
the  feelings,  of  deliberation,  and  of  the  will.  But  all  this 
belongs  as  yet  to  the  inward  sphere  ;  the  resolution  is  an  ideal 
union  of  the  will  with  the  end,  but  already  with  inward 
reference  to  the  future  and  to  the  outward  realization  of  the 
ideal  by  means  of  the  deed  of  the  active  will.  The  end  must 
all  the  time  remain  present  as  an  object  of  thought  and 
volition,  if  the  act  is  to  be  an  act  formally  complete.     The 

^    Jas.  i.   15,   i'Zi^vfiia  auXXafiiuira,. 


132  §  11.  man's  psychical  constitution. 

end,  as  an  end  placed  before  the  conscious  will  by  virtue  of 
the  resolution  to  realize  it,  is  purioosc  [Germ.  Vorsatz] ;  an  act 
is  a  purposed  or  deliberate  [Germ,  vorsdizlich]  act  when  it 
takes  place  on  the  basis  of  a  preceding  resolution  which  ended 
the  deliberation,  or  of  a  resolution  in  which  the  end  is  set 
before  the  present  will  as  an  end  to  be  realized  in  the  future. 
But  from  the  deliberate  act  is  still  to  be  distinguished  the 
intentional  act.  The  act  is  intentional,  not  merely  purposed, 
when  the  self-consciousness,  consciously  conceiving  of  the  end 
as  one  that  is  willed,  is  held  fast,  together  with  the  means,  by 
the  will  which  is  directed  towvards  the  attainment  of  the  end.' 
We  see  from  this  what  a  progressive,  composite  operation  a 
complete  act  is. 

The  final  factor,  after  the  desire  (which  itself  rests  on  the 
feeling  of  worth  and  on  the  consciousness  which  fixes  upon  the 
ends  to  be  aimed  at)  and  after  the  decision,  is  the  deed.  The 
end,  having  taken  the  form  of  purpose  and  intention,  receives 
in  the  deed  its  embodiment  through  the  person.  The  end 
having  become  operative  as  a  cause  through  the  will,  the 
process  is  relatively  finished  in  the  product,  which  now 
becomes  a  subject  of  judgment  or  valuation.  The  finished 
deed  is  followed  by  a  state  of  repose  in  one's  self,  in  which  the 
doer  is  alone  with  himself,  becomes  conscious  of  himself  as 
such,  and  the  deed  returns  to  the  doer.  The  actor  returns  to 
a  state  of  calm  self-consciousness  or  feeling  in  such  a  way  that 
the  product  of  the  act  is  taken  in  as  a  part  of  the  feeling,  and 
so  the  feeling  which  assigns  value  again  finds  a  place.  In 
pleasure  or  pain  the  ego,  as  now  modified,  has  an  impression 
of  itself,  of  its  deed,  and  the  worth  of  the  deed.  The  estima- 
tion extends  to  the  productive  deed,  to  the  product,  and  to  the 
agent  with  whom  the  deed,  as  being  his  own  determination,  is 
connected.  For  the  agent  has  put  himself,  as  a  conscious  and 
voluntary  causality,  into  the  deed  ;  and  now  there  ensues,  with 
reference  to  such  a  complete  act,  also  a  complete  imimtation, 
which  is  at  the  same  time  a  taking  account  of  himself  by  the 
agent,  a  referring  of  the  deed  back  to  the  ego  as  a  unity,  as 

1  Eothe,  ed.  1,  §  196  [ed.  2,  ii.  §  226].  Herrmann,  Ueber  Vorsafz  unci  Ahsicht. 
Aristotle  distinguishes  purpose  and  intention  (TpoalfKn;  and  (iou\vKri;)  thus  :  the 
former  never  aims  at  the  impossible,  while  the  latter  may  ;  the  former  includes 
also  the  means,  while  the  latter  is  directed  only  to  the  end. 


THE  SOUL  AS  ACTIVITY  AND  AS  A  STATE.  133 

a  conscious  and  voluntary  cause.  Yet  the  reckoning  can 
establish,  on  the  ground  of  the  single  deed,  only  a  relative 
result,  since  the  total  worth  of  the  person  does  not  depend 
merely  on  a  single  act. 

7.  Relation  of  the  soul  as  an  activity  to  the  soul  as  a  state. — 
To  the  moral  constitution  belongs  not  merely  the  capacity  to 
pass  from  potentiality  into  activity,  and  further  into  act  aud 
deed  [cf.  p.  130].  It  is  also  an  essential  part  of  it  that  this 
putting  forth  of  one's  self  reacts  on  the  faculty  which  enables 
what  has  been  acquired  in  the  process  of  feeling,  thinking,  and 
willing  to  abide  as  a  possession  in  the  form  of  a  state.  This 
is  an  important  element  in  the  moral  endowment,  without 
which  there  could  be  no  actual  progress,  no  connection  in  self- 
culture.  The  activities  of  the  soul  are  not  mere  isolated 
movements,  passing  away  without  a  trace,  like  dying  corusca- 
tions ;  else  it  would  be  necessary  always  to  begin  absolutely 
anew.  On  the  contrary,  the  earlier  acts  become  steps  for  the 
later  acts,  in  that  they  leave  a  deposit  behind  them.  They 
pass  over,  especially  when  they  form  a  series,  into  a  state, 
either  of  a  permanent  or  of  a  transient  sort.  The  state  after 
the  act  is  no  longer  merely  a  state  of  repose  in  one's  self,  as 
before  the  act ;  but  rather  the  sensibilities  after  the  act 
receive,  through  the  quality  of  the  act,  a  modification  which, 
when  it  is  of  a  more  transient  sort,  is  called  mood.  The  mood 
constitutes  the  groundwork  on  which  cognition  and  volition 
impress  themselves  anew,  and  it  continues  to  make  itself  felt 
in  them. 

But  not  only  does  the  totality  of  the  man  thus  show  in 
his  sensibilities  an  after-effect  of  the  acts  ;  cognition  and  will' 
also,  as  faculties,  receive  in  reaction  from  the  acts  of  cognitioni 
and  volitioh  a  modification  of  a  permanent  kind.  The  soul 
in  the  exercise  of  cognition  and  will  becomes  characterized 
by  its  own  acts.  The  thing  perceived  and  willed  comes, 
especially  after  repetition,  to  be  a  possession  and  property, 
belonging  after  a  sort  to  the  nature  of  this  faculty  that 
cognizes  and  wills.  The  volition  which  has  become  a  nature 
is  habit  ;  the  cognition  which  has  become  a  nature,  a 
permanent  possession  of  one's  own,  is  recollection  and  memory. 
Habit  is  the  memory  of  the  will;  memory  is  the  habit  of 
cognition.     The  blending  of  consciousness  and  will,  which  has 


134:  §  12.  man's  rational  constitution. 

become  a  persistent  thing,  or  a  state,  is  tendency  or  5cw^ 
\_Richtung] ;  the  blending  of  feeling,  consciousness,  and  will, 
when  it  has  become  a  state,  is  inclination,  in  which  the 
liveliness  of  feeling  is  preserved. 

CHAPTEE  THIRD. 

THE  RATIONAL  ELEMENT  IN  THE  MORAL  CONSTITUTION 

§  12. 

Man's  rational  constitution  consists  in  his  being  destined  for 
that  which  is  infinitely  worthy  (ultimately  for  that  which 
is  divine),  this  also  being  destined  for  him,  primarily 
for  his  soul,  which  thereby  becomes  reason  or  spirit. 
As  having  sensibilities  fitted  for  immediate  fellowship 
with  God,  the  soul  is  endowed  with  the  religious  reason ; 
in  so  far  as  it  is  addressed  by  the  infinite  in  the  form 
of  truth,  the  soul  is  endowed  with  the  intellectual 
reason  ;  finally,  so  far  forth  as  that  which  is  absolute 
for  the  will,  that  which  is  absolutely  good,  is  un- 
conditionally obligatory  for  it,  the  soul  is  endowed 
with  the  moral  reason.  The  faculties  of  intellectual, 
religious,  and  moral  reason  have,  notwithstanding  their 
common  ultimate  source,  a  relative  independence  of  one 
another,  and  are  in  time  dissolubly  connected ;  but  yet 
intrinsically  they  so  belong  together  that  only  with  and 
in  the  others  can  each  attain  its  full  development,  so 
that  a  circuit  of  the  mental  functions  is  required.  The 
rudiment  of  the  constitution  of  the  ethical  reason  lies 
in  the  mordl  feeling,  which  unfolds  itself  into  the  moral 
sense  and  impulse.  But  not  till  the  moral  sense  has 
become  conscience,  and  the  moral  impulse  has  become 
free  %vill,  not  till  there  is  this  antithesis  between  moral 
necessity  and  freedom,  the  members  of  which  are 
intrinsically  related  to  each  other  (correlates),  is  the 
complete  moral  constitution  actually  given. 


man's  capacity  for  morality  and  religion.        135 

1.  The  rationalness  of  the  human  soul,  however  it  may  be 
defined,  can  yet  be  found  only  in  the  relation  of  the  soul  to 
the  infinite,  or  in  the  fact  that  the  infinite  is  for  the  soul 
and  the  soul  for  the  infinite.  But  man  is  a  rational  being 
in  every  direction  of  his  mental  capacities  ;  the  infinite  is  for 
them  all,  for  each  according  to  its  kind.  The  infinite,  i.e. 
God,  as  related  to  the  sensibilities,  j)roduces  religion  or  piety ; 
as  related  to  cognition,  ideal  or  rational  knowledge ;  as 
related  to  the  will,  the  possibility  of  the  ethical  realm. 
Schleiermacher,  indeed,  thinks  that  the  Infinite,  or  God,  can 
be  apprehended  only  by  the  feelings,  not  by  cognition  or  by 
the  will,  because,  as  he  says,  these  two  imply  an  antithesis 
between  the  personal  subject  and  the  object  conceived  or 
willed,  whereas  God  is  elevated  above  the  antithesis.  But 
there  is  no  reason  to  deny  that  the  antithesis  between 
finite  and  infinite  exists  for  God  also ;  for  He  knows  Himself 
to  be  infinite,  and  the  world  at  the  same  time  to  be  different 
from  Himself.  But,  further,  the  religious  feeling  apprehends 
God  as  objective,  not  as  subjective ;  and  if  it  be  said  that 
man,  when  he  knows  and  wills,  is  finite,  absolutely  inadequate 
and  incompetent  to  apprehend  God,  it  is  to  be  replied :  man 
is  finite  in  feeling  too.  Conversely,  since  Schleiermacher  does 
not  deny  that  morality  is  of  infinite  worth,  and  can  yet  be  an 
•object  of  will  and  thought,  it  is  clear  that  finiteness  does  not 
hinder  one  from  being,  throughout  his  whole  spiritual  nature, 
susceptible  to  the  Infinite,  or  God,  i.e.  from  participating,  as 
to  one's  susceptibility,  in  the  Infinite. 

But  though  now  there  is  given  the  natural  endowment  in 
man  for  piety,  for  morality,  and  for  the  apprehension  of  truth, 
though  they  all  subsist  in  a  certain  unity  in  the  rational 
constitution,  yet  this  unity  does  not  obliterate  their  difference. 
They  are,  in  fact,  in  their  formative  period  only  dissolubly 
connected  with  one  another,  and  have,  in  relation  to  one  another, 
a  certain  self-subsistence  and  incle'pende7ice,  although  they  all, 
each  for  itself,  come  to  perfection  only  with  and  through  the 
others.  We  consider  this  especially  with  respect  to  the 
relation  between  the  inoral  and  the  religious  side  of  the 
rational  nature. 

2.  It  might  be  said  that  the  ultimate  source  of  morality, 
as  well  as  of  religion,    is  God.      The    two   are,   it  may  be 


136  §  12.  man's  rational  constitution. 

thought,  so  intimately  connected,  that  where  there  is  faith  in 
God,  there  must  be  morality  also,  and  that  where  the  mind 
has  taken  a  sceptical  or  even  negative  attitude  towards  the 
idea  of  God,  there  too  all  morality  must  he  wanting.  But 
that  the  two,  religion  and  morality,  are  distinct,  is  clear  from 
the  fact  that  faith  in  God  does  not  of  necessity  immediately 
lay  hold  on  the  will  and  the  cognition ;  and  this  is  so  not 
merely  where  the  conceptions  of  God  are  imperfect  and 
untrue.  For  a  low  degree  of  morality  may  co-exist  even 
with  comparatively  pure  conceptions  of  God,  and  a  high 
degree  of  morality  even  with  imperfect  knowledge  of  God. 
Furthermore, — a  fact  to  which  Eothe  and  Ernest  Naville 
direct  attention, — persons  are  observed,  especially  in  the 
cultivated  classes,  who  have  in  their  inmost  being  no  fixed 
or  clear  religious  conviction,  rather,  at  the  most,  a  God 
concealed  from  their  own  consciousness,  who  yet  manifests 
Himself  as  operating  in  them  in  their  integrity  and  social 
virtues.  Such  instances  occur  especially  in  times  when 
widespread  doubt  has  become  a  prejudice,  and  has,  as  it 
were,  deposited  itself  upon  the  consciousness,  though  this 
deposit  has  not  penetrated  into  the  depths  of  the  soul. 
There  are  persons  whose  religious  convictions  have  become 
ruins,  while  their  conscience  still  remains,  like  a  solitary 
column,  as  a  monument  of  a  demolished  structure  ;  they  may 
still  have  a  lively  sense  of  what  is  noble  and  pure,  a  disgust 
at  everything  bad  and  low.  The  sense  of  duty  may  still 
continue  for  a  while  in  man,  as  a  sense  of  the  nobility  of 
human  nature,  after  its  religious  support  is  lost.  Something 
similar  is  seen  where  a  religious  culture  has  not  yet  been 
reached  at  all,  but  where  there  is  an  ethico-humanitarian 
culture. 

Shall  we  now  say,  perhaps,  in  order  to  solve  this  enigma. 
These  persons,  too,  have  religion  ;  or  even.  They  are  un- 
conscious Christians,  since  Christianity  consists  in  morality 
as  well  as  in  piety  ?  Is  their  virtuous  life,  their  devotion  to 
a  supersensuous  rule  of  duty,  to  be  regarded  as  religion  ?  Or, 
on  the  other  hand,  shall  we,  instead  of  thus  identifying 
religion  and  morality,  say,  There  is  no  essential  connection 
between  the  two ;  perfect  morality  is  conceivable  without 
reli'non  ?       Neither,    we    answer.       In    the  first    place,    the 


EELATION  OF  MORALITY  TO  RELIGION'.  137 

identification  of  the  two  is  excluded  by  the  fact  that  they  can 
become  separated,  and  can  maintain  a  certain  independence  in 
relation  to  each  other.  And  this  independence  has  its  objec- 
tive ground.  Ethical  good  is,  in  the  conscience  and  in  the 
ethically  constituted  reason,  an  innate  possession  of  the  soul, 
and  in  such  wise  that  it  requires  realization,  as  being  that 
which  corresponds  to  the  reason  and  dignity  of  man.  This  is 
a  possession  of  the  practical  reason  even  without  conscious 
regress  to  the  primary  ethical  Being,  or  God.  The  opinion 
can,  at  least  for  a  time,  be  held,  that  the  conscience  is 
not  a  derivative  source  of  moral  truth,  but  the  sufficient 
source,  not  needing  a  deeper  foundation.  If,  now,  the  know- 
ledge be  wanting  that  conscience  has  its  foundation  in 
religion,  then  there  is  indeed  a  religious  blindness,  that  is,  a 
deficiency,  which  hinders  the  will  from  having  recourse  to  the 
primal  source  of  moral  power  ;  but  the  moral  law  and  the 
consciousness  of  it  may  exist  in  man  even  when  he  does  not 
know  their  origin.  God  has  indeed  a  connection,  not  only 
with  the  world  in  general,  but  also  with  those  who  do  not 
thank  Him,  or  who  even  deny  Him,  Yet  everything  good 
which  they  do,  they  do  through  His  power.  But  man  is  able 
to  disregard  this  relation  of  God  to  him,  and  to  dwell  in 
the  sphere  of  that  morality  or  absolute  worth  which  is 
merely  secondary.  The  relative  indej^endence  of  religion, 
however,  is  clear  from  the  fact  that  piety  and  the  interest 
in  it  may  have  advanced  in  a  man  farther  than  the  interest 
in  the  other  departments  of  morals.  Moral  sense  and  moral 
impulse  may  be  comparatively  sluggish  and  undeveloped. 

But,  in  the  second  place,  the  essential  connection  of  the  two 
is  nevertheless  just  as  certain  (Matt,  xxii,  37,  39).  It 
will  always  be  a  stumbling-block  to  a  healthy  feeling,  when 
a  person  who  especially  emphasizes  piety  shows  himself  in 
moral  relations  lax,  selfish,  quarrelsome,  censorious,  destitute 
of  moral  delicacy.  The  fact  remains,  that  morality  belongs 
to  piety,  if  the  piety  is  at  all  of  the  right  sort.  For 
piety  must  be  living  fellowship  not  merely  with  the  omni- 
potent, majestic,  righteous  God,  but  also  with  the  God  of  holy 
love,  so  that  it  is  a  defect  in  piety  itself,  if  it  is  not  con- 
formed to  morality. 

But  morality  likewise   can   be   neither   perfect   nor   pure, 


138  §  12.  man's  rational  constitution. 

unless  it  includes  in  the  love  of  goodness  also  the  love  of  the 
primal  source  of  goodness,  the  personal  God — in  other  words, 
is,  or  becomes,  piety.  This  is  requisite  not  merely  for 
moral  culture  and  intelligence,  but  also  especially  for  the 
reason  that,  if  that  secondary  form  of  the  good  which  exists 
in  the  consciousness  and  will  of  man  should  be  assumed 
to  be  the  highest  and  best,  the  necessary  consequence  would 
be  self-deification,  that  is,  a  want  of  the  virtue  of  humility. 
But  this  want  disfigures  even  the  goodness  which  may  already 
exist,  being  a  sort  of  selfishness,  even  thougli  a  comparatively 
intellectual  form  of  it,  as  is  shown  by  the  pride  of  virtue 
among  the  Stoics.  Finally,  it  would  be  an  error  to  suppose 
that  morality  has  as  firm  a  basis,  without  reference  to  God,  as 
with  it.  If  the  atheist  denies  this,  then  the  objective  sacred- 
ness  and  absolute  inviolableness  of  the  good  itself  will  liecome 
unsettled,  and  that  solitary  column  will  fall  amid  the  tempta- 
tions and  storms  of  life.  But  if  the  atheist  seeks  to  hold 
fast  the  absoluteness  of  duty,  he  cannot  be  satisfied  with 
looking  upon  himself  alone  as  the  binding  authority ;  he 
must  recognise  the  good  as  a  power  independent  of  himself ; 
and  this  must  lead  him,  if  only  he  developes  his  con- 
sciousness on  all  sides,  back  to  God  as  the  supreme  sanction 
of  all  obligation.  Thus  it  appears  that  a  morality  without 
religion  after  all  rests  only  upon  an  obscure  view  of  things, 
which  needs  to  be  clarified  and  thereby  come  to  a  decision 
either  for  religion  or  against  it. 

Similar  to  the  relation  between  morality  and  religion  is  the 
relation  of  cognition  to  both.  Knowledge,  too,  does  not  always 
keep  equal  pace  with  these,  and  is  therefore  relatively  separable, 
whether  going  before  or  lagging  behind  ;  but  it  remains  as 
the  province  of  the  will  to  blend  true  knowledge  with  religion 
and  morality  :  for  wisdom  too  is  a  virtue. 

3.  Morality  shares  with  knowledge  and  with  religion  the 
relation  to  that  which  is  of  infinite  worth.  But  the  pecu- 
liarity of  morality,  as  over  against  these  two,  consists,  accord- 
ing to  what  has  been  said,  in  the  fact  that  in  the  case 
of  morality  that  which  has  absolute  worth  is  put  under 
the  category  of  the  will ;  it  is  the  absolute  for  the  vnll 
which  is  primarily  had  in  view.  But  morality,  together 
with  the  will,  embraces    all    realms,  including  religion  and 


THE  MOEAL  WILL  AND  MORAL  FEELING.  139 

knowledge,  and  is  in  turn  embraced  by  these  ;  it  embraces 
them,  however,  in  its  own  way,  from  the  point  of  view  of 
the  will.  But  the  moral  will  on  its  part  can  operate  only 
upon  the  condition  that  there  is  a  consciousness  of  what 
is  morally  good,  and  that  the  feelings  are  stirred  by  an 
ideal  delight  in  the  good.  Neither  the  consciousness  nor 
the  feelings  need  for  this  reason  to  necessitate  the  will ; 
especially  the  moral  feeling  must  not  be  allowed  to  become 
of  itself  an  overpowering  impulse ;  but,  first  of  all,  the 
good  in  its  majesty  and  sacredness  must  be  brought  to 
consciousness,  in  order  tlmt  the  personal  will  may  assume  an 
attitude  with  reference  to  it.  This  consciousness,  in  which 
the  moral  sense  and  the  conscience  become  active,  represents 
a  necessary  principle,  but  necessary  in  the  sense  that  it  is 
addressed  to  freedom,  and  in  such  a  way  that,  by  this  very 
consciousness  of  the  morally  necessary,  the  personality  is 
invested  with  its  rights  as  a  free  personality.  But  the 
manner  in  which  in  the  temporal  life  the  moral  faculties 
gradually  manifest  themselves  in  coming  to  their  perfection, 
under  tlie  continual  agency  of  God,  cannot  be  discussed  till 
we  come  to  the  Second  Division.  In  the  moment  of  a  man's 
creation,  freedom  and  conscience  do  not  as  yet  actually  exist, 
but  there  is  a  susceptibility  in  the  man  for  having  that 
which  is  absolutely  obligatory  and  worthy  further  inwrought 
into  him. 

4.  The  Moral  Feeling. — We  consider  here  somewhat  more 
closely  the  moral  feeling,  which  issues  in  moral  sense  and 
impulse,  reserving  the  more  extended  discussion  of  it  for 
Division  II.  The  moral  feeling  is  fundamental  in  the  con- 
stitution of  the  ethical  reason  ;  it  is  originally  the  emotion 
excited  in  the  rational  creature  when  the  idea  of  morality 
moves  or  strikes  the  heart,  that  is,  it  is  a  practical  feeling 
of  the  worth  of  things  (§  11.  3).  It  is  not  mere  sensa- 
tion, it  has  reference  to  an  object ;  it  is  a  feeling  of  the 
good  which  ought  to  be,  and  which  by  its  value  awakens 
ideal  pleasure,  as  also  ideal  displeasure  is  awakened  towards 
its  contrary.  The  ideal  displeasure  can  co-exist  with  sensuous 
pleasure,  and  ideal  pleasure  with  sensuous  displeasure. 

That  the  moral  feeling  forms  the  foundation  for  the  moral 
development  is,  however,  disputed,  especially  by  Kant,  who 


140  §  12.  man's  kational  constitution. 

denies  that  the  ethical  nature  has  its  original  existence  in  a 
feeling  which  comes  to  be  moral  impulse  and  moral  sense. 
Feeling,  according  to  him,  is  something  only  pathological  and 
physical.  But  there  are  also  mental  feelings  and  impulses, 
which  belong  to  the  reason,  and  are  not  merely  of  an  animal 
sort;  in  the  impulse  to  get  knowledge,  also,  the  animating 
principle  must  be  the  intellectual  feeling  of  the  value  of  truth 
as  a  good.  For  sensuous  feelings  are  rather  mere  sensations. 
And  the  fear  is  unwarranted,  that  from  the  sensibilities 
danger  is  threatened  to  freedom,  since  it  is  certain  that 
morality  in  the  strict  sense  rests  on  self-determination,  and, 
further,  that  the  will  must  influence  feeling  and  cognition 
also.  But  the  existence  of  a  moral  constitution,  antecedent 
to  morality,  must  form  the  prerequisite  of  all  ethical  self- 
culture.  It  may  be  called  the  natural  constitution,  if  by 
nature  is  understood  the  immediate  product  of  creation, 
which,  however,  is  not  merely  a  finite  ^vai<;,  but  the  starting- 
point  of  the  moral  being,  without  which  there  would  be  no 
connecting  link  for  any  further  moral  development.  For  if 
the  moral  sensibilities  were  wanting,  then  all  subsequent 
imposition  of  law  would  be  without  any  necessary  or  intrinsic 
conformity  to  the  nature  of  man,  and  would  for  ever  exhibit 
the  appearance  of  caprice  and  externality,  being  necessarily 
foreign  to  the  inmost  nature  of  man.  But  the  consequence 
of  this  would  be,  that  he  would  be  incapable  of  discerning  the 
truth  or  inward  excellence  of  the  proffered  good,  and  hence 
could  not  pass  over  from  the  state  of  servitude  into  the  state 
of  freedom.  The  consequence  of  exaggerating  the  indepen- 
dence of  morality,  as  over  against  everything  natural  which  is 
innate,  would  be,  accordingly,  that  no  way  would  lead  beyond 
caprice  and  bondage  into  a  moral  perception  of  one's  own. 

But,  we  still  inquire,  is  not  feeling  dangerous  to  freedom  ? 
It  can,  on  the  very  contrary,  be  only  promotive  of  free  will. 
We  are  not  speaking  of  sentimental  feelings,  enfeebling  to  the 
will,  but  of  the  moral  feelings.  How  can  the  free  will  be 
impaired  by  our  having  the  power  to  make  present  to  the 
mind,  in  ideal  pleasure,  the  worth  of  what  is  good,  and,  in 
displeasure,  the  worthlessness  of  what  is  evil  ?  The  ideal 
pleasure  consists  perfectly  well  with  freedom,  is  indeed  itself 
a  proof  that  the  good  is  something  which  is  not  foreign  to  the 


RELATION  OF  FEELING  TO  FREEDOM.  141 

nature  of  man,  bvit  is  in  harmony  with  his  inmost  being,  and 
really  sets  his  freedom  free.  Where  there  is  pleasure,  there 
is  freedom  from  obstructions  to  life,  even  if  these  be  only 
something  foreboded.  Nor  does  it  contradict  this  pleasure 
and  this  freedom,  that  with  them  may  be  connected  the 
consciousness  of  the  ideal  necessity  of  the  good,  since  the 
good  is  the  truth  of  one's  own  nature.  This  moral  feeling, 
of  which  the  sense  of  right  is  only  the  one  negative  side,  and 
which  forms  the  starting-point  of  conscience,  makes  itself 
knowm  at  first  on  occasion  of  coming  into  contact  with  a 
single  good  thing  that  awakens  pleasure ;  and  it  is  not 
necessary  that  it  immediately  come  to  a  definite  conception 
of  God.  Nevertheless  this  must  take  place  in  course  of  time. 
As  the  religious  feeling  is  perfected  by  becoming  also  a 
consciousness  of  absolute  dependence  having  an  ethical 
character,  so  it  is  essential  to  morality  that  it  be  not  merely 
love  to  a  single  good  thing,  but  rather  that  in  the  single  thing 
that  which  is  good  be  itself  seized  and  chosen,  yes,  that  the 
primordial  good,  the  personal  God,  be  loved  in  the  single  good 
thing ;  and  thus  morality  becomes  religious. 

Note. — The  New  Testament  also  speaks  of  the  ideal  pleasure 
of  the  sVw  civ&pM'jog  in  the  good,  thus  recognising  the  moral 
feeling  (Kom.  vii.  22). 

SECOND    SECTION. 

INDIVIDUALITY  IN  MAN'S  MORAL  ENDOWiMENT  (§  9&). 

§  13. 

In  addition  to  the  endowment  common  to  all  men,  there  is 
that  which  belongs  to  every  individual  singly,  or,  in 
other  words,  peculiarit)/,  in  consequence  of  which  mankind 
appears  in  the  form  of  a  manifold  variety  of  beings, 
and  by  which  alone  a  real  ethical  cosmos  is  rendered 
possible. 

Note. — Three  points  are  of  importance  in  this  section : — 

1.  To  recognise  the  necessity  of  individuality. 

2.  To  discern  wherein  the  general  essence  of  it  consists. 

3.  To  notice  its  chief  sorts. 


142  §  13.    INDIVIDUALITY.       NECESSITY  OF  IT. 

1.  The  Sacred  Scriptures  recognise  both  the  existence  and 
the  necessity  of  individuality  in  the  most  express  manner ; 
and  the  Apostle  Paul  especially  has  devoted  magnificent 
passages  to  it,  Cf.  especially  1  Cor.  xii.  4  sqq. ;  Eph.  iv.  11  ; 
Eom.  xii.  4  sqq.  Here  belongs  the  figure  of  the  aSifxa  and 
the  multitude  of  fJieXr],  which  serves  to  promote  the  prosperity 
both  of  the  whole  and  of  the  parts.  The  distinctions  of 
individuality  are  constituted  by  nature  itself,  but  are  not 
effaced  by  Christianity  ;  on  the  contrary,  to  the  Holy  Spirit 
is  ascribed  the  twofold  office  of  being  the  source  of  variety  in 
the  charismata,  and  of  forming  the  bond  of  their  union  (1  Cor, 
xii.  4  sqq.).  The  twelve  different  precious  stones,  also,  each 
of  which  has  its  own  colour,  and  which  belong  to  the  founda- 
tion of  the  city  of  God  (liev.  xxi.  18  sqq.),  are  to  be  reckoned 
as  belonging  here. 

2.  The  necessity  that  that  which  is  individual  coexist  with 
that  which  is  common,  obvious  as  it  seems,  has  yet  not  been 
distinctly  recognised  till  the  most  modern  times.  The  ante- 
Christian  times,  in  which  even  personality  recedes  behind 
nature  and  the  objective  regulations  of  society,  were  still 
further  from  grasping  the  notion  of  individual  peculiarity. 
Within  the  Christian  era,  the  Eoman  Catholic  Church  likewise 
has  fostered  individuality  but  little ,  it  has  aimed  more  at  a 
uniform  ecclesiastical  type  of  character,  but  has  not  striven 
to  make  each  person  free,  and  certain  of  salvation ;  the 
Church,  rather,  is  the  all-dominating  moral  personality.  In  a 
perverted  v;ay,  to  be  sure,  individual  peculiarity  has  found 
place  in  this  Church,  in  the  distinction  between  common 
virtue  and  a  higher  virtue.  And  even  when  individuality 
was  tolerated,  it  yet  was  not  in  theory  approved  as  something 
to  be  cultivated.  The  ethics  of  the  Church  treated  of  right 
action  as  if  it  were  only  a  manifold  repetition  of  one  and  the 
same  moral  ideal  without  difference,  as  if  duty  related  only  to 
that  which  is  common  to  all.  On  the  other  hand,  a  uniform 
ecclesiastical  ethics  could  not  possibly  embrace  everything 
individual ;  so  the  obverse  of  this  strict  uniformity  was  a 
realm  of  things  morally  indefinite  and  given  over  to  option 
or  caprice. 

Individuality  is  a  fact,  whether  it  be  ignored  and  resisted, 
or  recognised.     A  system   of  ethics  which  would  have  only 


ETHICAL  SIGNIFICANCE  OF  INDIVIDUALITY.  143 

Avhat  is  common  to  all  regulated  by  duty,  acquits  and  aljsolves 
from  moral  rule  a  whole  section  of  personal  life,  and  abandons 
it  to  itself,  or  else  tends  to  impair  and  obliterate  individuality 
by  a  uniform  rule.  In  the  first  case,  we  have  a  domain  of 
that  which  is  held  to  be  not  morally  imperative,  where  the 
so-called  permissible  or  optional  actious  are  said  to  belong, 
which  at  the  most  can  only  be  the  subject  of  advice  from  the 
consilia  evangdica.  But  then  the  moral  law,  as  an  imperative 
authority,  w^ould  have  no  right  to  assert  itself  always  and 
everywhere  in  human  life ;  there  would  be  a  sphere  lying  too 
low  to  be  ethically  affected — a  sphere  below  morality,  below 
duty — which  is  to  remain  given  over  to  the  free  pleasure  of 
man,  because  morality  lays  no  claim  to  it.  But  there  imme- 
diately connects  itself  with  this,  as  the  obverse  of  it,  that 
which  is  above  duty,  supererogatory.  For  when  a  man  so 
uses  his  right  over  this  sphere  which  is  at  his  disposal,  that 
he  of  his  own  free  choice  {i.e.  caprice)  sacrifices  what  he 
would  not  be  bound  to  sacrifice,  then  he  gains  for  himself  a 
merit  for  doing  more  than  duty  requires.  Thus  the  realm  of 
morals  suffers  a  double  loss ;  what  is  below  morality,  and 
what  is  above  morality,  fall  out  of  its  sphere.  So  closely 
connected  with  great  moral  errors  is  the  failure  to  recognise 
individuality  as  something  willed  by  the  Creator,  and  hence 
to  be  guarded  as  a  matter  of  duty. 

The  Bcforriiation,  it  is  true,  emphasized  personality  and 
personal  assurance  of  salvation,  as  also  the  unity  of  all  in 
faith,  and  the  equal  rights  of  all  the  members  (Gal.  iii.  28; 
1  Cor.  xiv.  14-26).  And  the  evangelical  principle  of  faith, 
according  to  which  we  are  all  one  in  Christ,  by  no  means 
implies  the  extinction  of  all  individuality,  the  reduction  of  all 
individuals  to  one  and  the  same  pattern.  The  meaning  of 
this  principle  is,  rather,  that,  however  different  in  other 
respects  believers  may  be,  they  themselves,  in  their  God- 
given  individuality,  have  equal  worth.  jSTevertheless  the 
Evangelical  Church  has  long  enough  held  fast  only  the 
negative  side  of  this  truth,  namely,  that  "in  spite  of"  in- 
dividual differences  there  subsists  an  equality  in  the  worth 
of  persons ;  but  it  has  not  held  that  this  subsists  by  and  in 
this  very  individuality  itself.  Spener,  likewise,  does  not  get 
beyond  this.      The  philosophy  of  Kant  and  Hegel  also  is  not 


144  §13.    INDIVIDUALITY. 

favourable  to  individuality ;  they  see  in  it  only  a  limitation, 
not  the  condition  of  the  realization  of  the  moral  cosmos. 
Only  Leibnitz  and  Schleiermacher  form  an  exception ;  the 
first  work  of  Leibnitz  treats  de  2^'>''^ncipio  individui,  and  his 
doctrine  of  monads  seeks  to  give  a  metaphysical  basis  to 
individuality. 

3.  The  variety  of  different  individualities  becomes  an 
ethical  cosmos.  It  might  be  urged  against  this  variety,  that 
the  likeness  of  all,  rather  than  diversity,  would  seem  to  be 
favourable  to  unity  and  love,  and  that  it  would  be  better  able 
to  make  all  into  one  connected  whole.  But  distinction  need 
mean  neither  contradiction  nor  separation ;  and  on  the  other 
hand,  a  uniform  sameness  is  not  to  be  confounded  with  a 
living  oneness.  Plainly,  an  organism  is  not  possible  except 
through  a  variety  in  the  mutual  relation  of  members,  through 
a  union  of  what  is  common  and  of  what  is  individual.  Only 
an  organism  which  is  not  a  mere  continuity  can  be  called  a 
unit  possessing  life. 

But  against  the  necessity  and  the  moral  right  of  indivi- 
duality, it  might  also  be  urged,  that  every  single  individual 
is  meant  to  become  perfect  (Matt.  v.  48),  and  that,  if  every 
one  should  become  perfect  as  the  Father  in  heaven  is  perfect, 
there  would  be  no  room  left  for  a  diversity  of  individuali- 
ties. For,  it  may  be  said,  this  diversity  is  possible  only  in 
case  each  has  something  which  the  others  have  not ;  and 
this,  accordingly,  would  imply  the  general  imperfection  of  the 
different  individuals.  But  we  reply :  If  it  belonged  to  the 
Christian  notion  of  perfection  that  every  individual  should 
have  just  the  same  excellences  as  every  other,  then  it  would 
follow  that  at  least  in  the  state  of  perfection  all  individuality 
must  give  place  to  uniformity.  But  this  would  be  in  direct 
contradiction  to  the  high  importance  which,  as  just  shown, 
the  Bible  ascribes  to  individuality,  and  which  does  not  allow 
it  to  be  regarded  as  only  a  transient  thing.  With  perfection 
{reXeioTTj'i)  in  the  Christian  sense  it  is  entirely  compatible 
that  the  individuals  should  have  and  keep  different  in- 
dividualities. The  moral  goal  which  is  for  all,  and  which 
can  already  be  approximately  attained  by  Christians,  is  not 
opposed  to  a  manifoldness  of  individual  character,  but  to 
that  which  is  still  inconsistent  with  the  vofio'i  reXew;  of  the 


NECESSITY  AND  PERMANENCE  OF  IT.  145 

Christian,  and  to  the  indolence  which  has  as  yet  kept  men 
from  making  their  own  the  excellences  which  belong  to  the 
perfection  of  the  individual.  There  are,  besides,  other 
excellences  quite  conceivable,  which  do  not  at  all  belong 
to  the  ideal  of  every  man,  and  the  want  of  which,  therefore, 
is  not  to  be  regarded  as  a  defect  inconsistent  with  perfection. 
Certain  faculties  may  be  stronger  in  one  individual  than  in 
another,  provided  only  all  the  other  faculties  are  harmoniously 
adjusted  to  these,  whether  it  be  by  an  intensification  of 
them,  or  by  a  different  mutual  relation  of  the  faculties  in 
general.  Thus  for  each  individual  that  perfection  is  possible 
which  is  required  by  the  moral  ideal  that  is  applicable 
to  him. 

Therefore  we  cannot  concede  that  it  is  only  in  the 
uniform  perfection  of  all  that  the  bond  of  unity  is  secured 
which  binds  individuals  firmly  together.  On  the  contrary, 
if  all  had  everything  alike,  if  each  one  were  the  whole,  and 
so  in  no  need  of  being  supplemented,  there  would  be,  instead 
of  living  unity,  only  co-existence  side  by  side  like  that  of 
atoms.  Then  it  would  be  to  tlie  whole  a  matter  of  indiffer- 
ence whether  a  part  were  lacking  to  it ;  while  to  the  indi- 
viduals it  would  be  no  less  a  matter  of  indifference  whether 
a  part  were  lacking  or  suffering.  What  would  love  have  tci 
exchange,  moreover,  if  all  were  alike  in  everything?  There- 
fore creative  love,  because  aiming  at  a  living  unity,  has  willed, 
the  apparent  opposite  of  unity,  viz.  diversity,  but  yet  has. 
willed  it  for  the  sake  of  the  unity,  and  accordingly  so  that 
the  variety  is  embraced  and  controlled  by  a  higher  principle.. 
This  involves  that  the  many,  in  spite  of  their  diversity,  are-, 
yet  all  so  constituted  that  all  can  be  for  all,  that  is,  at  least 
have  universal  susceptibility  for  all  the  varieties  which  inhere: 
in  the  individuals.  For,  of  course,  there  are  not  various- 
species  of  reason,  as  nature  exhibits  a  variety  of  species ; 
there  is  only  one  species  of  reason,  and  this  bears  the 
character  of  universality,  so  that  everything  existent  may  be 
for  it — if  not  for  it  to  produce,  yet  for  it  to  receive.  And 
thus  the  necessity  and  the  right  of  individuality  consists 
perfectly  well  with  the  fact  that  all,  however  different,  are 
made  for  mutual  fellowship. 

4.   On   the  (jcacral   'iiature  of  individuality. — Even  in  the 

K 


146  §  13.    INDIVIDUALITY.       GENERAL  NATUEE  OF  IT. 

Middle  Ages,  which  otherwise  did  little  justice  to  individuality, 
inquiries  were  made  as  to  what  in  general  it  rested  on,  as 
Leibnitz  sets  forth  in  detail  in  the  treatise  above  mentioned. 
Various  possibilities  may  be  adduced,  {a)  It  is,  of  course, 
evident  that  diversity  of  place  and  time  cannot  constitute  the 
characteristic  feature  of  individuality.  For  if  we  assume 
only  a  plurality  of  one  and  the  same  being,  with  difference 
of  place  and  of  time,  then  it  would  follow,  that  two  in- 
dividuals who  exchanged  their  place  would  be  transformed 
into  each  other ;  and  also  that  they  would  cease  to  be 
different,  if  they  existed  at  the  same  time  and  were  of  the 
same  age. 

(6)  It  would  therefore  be  necessary  to  add  that  the  differ- 
ence of  place  and  time  brings  with  it  different  influences 
of  the  outward  world,  especially  of  the  world  of  humanity, 
and  that  thus  differences  of  individuality  arise.  But,  as  to 
this  last  point,  whence  come,  in  the  world  of  humanity  itself, 
the  different  influences  ?  The  question  would  be  only  carried 
farther  back.  And,  in  general,  we  should  be  assumed  to  be 
purely  passive  in  our  individuality,  dependent  on  something 
outside. 

(c)  Others,  taking  as  their  starting-point  the  essence  of 
humanity  in  general,  suppose  that  individuality  comes  about 
by  means  of  differences  in  the  division,  limitation,  or  privation 
of  human  being.  The  essence  of  mankind,  it  is  said, 
although  in  itself  homogeneous,  is  in  some  persons  more,  in 
others  less,  limited.  Each  individual  is  therefore  different 
from  the  others  purely  by  reason  of  a  different  quantity  of 
human  being.  But  underlying  this  is  the  supposition  that 
properly  it  is  involved  in  the  idea  of  every  individual  that  he 
ought  to  be  the  whole,  by  which  again  of  course  variety 
would  be  abolished.  Besides  this,  it  is  not  satisfactory  to 
treat  of  mind  as  mere  quantity. 

{d)  Especially  common  is  the  opinion  that  individuality  is 
derived  from  the  body,  or  from  the  sphere  of  matter,  as 
representing  existence  in  its  divided  state  in  the  world.  So  the 
Arabic  Aristotelians,  also  Albertus  Magnus.^     Diversity,  it  is 

^  Ritter,  Geschichie  der  christl.  Philosophie,  1858,  i.  p.  635  sqq.  Rothe  also 
says,  individuality  has  its  original  abode  in  tlie  material  side  of  human  nature. 
Theol.  Ethih,  2nd  ed.  §  1.31,  165,  167,  174,  176,  215,  219. 


DIFFERENT  VIEWS  CONSIDERED.  147 

sometimes  said,  cannot  come  from  mind,  mind  being  that 
which  is  identical  in  all,  while  yet  mind  is  variously  deter- 
mined by  the  various  admixture  of  material  elements.  But 
the  assumption  that  mind  is  in  itself  everywhere  one  and  the 
same  thing,  while  yet  it  would  still  have  to  be  the  province 
of  this  identical  mind  to  subjugate  matter  and  impress  upon 
it  the  stamp  of  mind,  would  again  lead  to  all  individuals 
becoming  alike  in  the  state  of  perfection.  Variety  would  last 
only  so  long  as  mind  had  as  yet  failed  to  make  itself  com- 
pletely felt ;  this,  therefore,  leads  back  to  the  assumption  of 
the  transientness  of  individuality. 

(e)  In  order  to  escape  the  error  which  makes  not  merely 
mind  in  its  utterances,  but  also  individuality  in  its  essential 
nature,  dependent  on  matter,  we  may  try,  with  Origen,  to 
derive,  conversely,  individuality  from  the  mind  itself,  namely, 
from  its  freedom.  All  souls  were,  according  to  him,  created 
alike ;  they  have  become  different  only  by  the  different  use 
of  their  liberty, — a  good  or  a  bad  use.  Upon  this  inner 
history  depends,  further,  also  the  bodily  organization  or  the 
individuality.  But  according  to  this,  if  all  made  an  equally 
good  use  of  freedom,  they  would  become  the  same ;  there  are, 
however,  other  individual  differences  than  that  between  good 
and  evil  with  their  degrees.  We  find,  consequently,  that  the 
one-sided  derivation  of  individuality  whether  from  mind  on 
the  one  hand,  or  from  the  body  on  the  other,  leads  to  the 
same  result,  namely,  that  individuality  would  be  destroyed 
by  perfect  culture.  But  this  is  in  plain  contradiction  with 
experience.  Just  where  the  mind  is  least  cultivated,  as  among 
savages,  the  greatest  resemblance  is  observed  even  in  respect 
to  the  body ;  culture  makes  the  individual  stamp  more 
sharply  defined ;  culture  is  to  be  carefully  distinguished  from 
the  mere  polish  of  culture. 

We  cannot,  then,  find  the  sufficient  principle  of  individua- 
tion in  anything  merely  external,  in  mere  limitation,  or  in 
quantitative  distinction;  and  freedom  also  is  inadequate  to 
account  for  it.  If  this  be  so,  and  if  we  recoc^nise  it  as  beincc 
for  the  good  of  the  permanent  universe  that  the  indi- 
vidual differences  among  mankind  should  be  permanent,  then 
only  one  opinion  is  left  to  us :  namely,  that  individuality  has 
not  arisen   from   empirical   causes,  merely   as   a   subsequent 


148  §  13.    INDIVIDUALITY. 

effect ;  it  is  a  creative  thought  of  God,  and  is  incorporated, 
as  an  eternally  abiding  factor,  into  the  very  notion  of  the 
human  race  itself.  Mankind  was  not  conceived  of  by  God 
as  a  unit  having  no  individual  parts,  but  only  as  consisting 
in  individuals,  even  though  the  realization  of  the  creative 
thought  may  not  be  brought  about  except  in  temporal  history 
and  through  secondary  causes.  The  spirit  of  the  whole  can 
nevertheless,  as  regulator,  govern  all  the  individuals ;  and  so 
much  the  more,  inasmuch  as  the  idea  of  each  single  individual 
within  this  unity  of  mankind  involves  in  it  that,  in  a  certain 
way,  each  has,  besides  his  own,  also  that  which  the  others 
have,  at  least  in  the  form  of  susceptibility  (they  are,  as 
Leibnitz  puts  it,  all  microcosms) ;  but  each  in  a  different 
manner  from  the  others.  And  since  the  individualities  can 
be  neither  merely  spiritual  nor  merely  corporeal,  but  present 
themselves  in  both  forms,  it  follows  that,  as  Leibnitz  expresses 
it,  every  being  is  individuated  in  its  entirety  {totum  ens  in  se 
foto  individuatur). 

Schleiermacher  expresses  himself  in  a  similar  manner ;  ^  he 
assumes,  to  be  sure,  that  through  its  connection  with  the 
body  the  soul  has  a  peculiar  modification ;  he  also  sees  a 
ground  for  individuality  in  the  relation  of  the  ego  to  the 
non-ego, — to  the  world,  in  respect  of  climate,  food,  nationality, 
education,  religion,  etc.  But  the  psychical  peculiarity,  he  says, 
must  nevertheless  be  implanted,  predetermined,  in  the  rudi- 
ments of  each  individual ;  each  has  his  peculiar  soul.  The 
outward  coefficients  govern  only  the  form,  or  sort,  of  the 
activity  of  that  which  is  already  fixed  inwardly  (the  potential 
individuality) ;  otherwise  self-activity  would  be  as  good  as 
null.  He  sums  it  up  as  follows : '  The  peculiarity  of  the 
individual  is  the  perfectly  definite  shaping  of  the  relation 
between  the  different  vital  functions  in  reference  to  the 
totality  of  things.  We  say,  therefore :  each  person  is  both 
physically  and  mentally  a  peculiar  combination  of  the  faculties 
belonging  to  the  genus  ;  and  the  whole  of  humanity  indi- 
vidualizes itself  in  each  one  in  a  particular  manner.  Man- 
kind, according  to  the  divine  idea,  does  not  exist  except  as  a 
variety  of  peculiar  persons,  who,  however,  belong  together  by 

'  Ckristliche  Sitte,  pp.  58  sqq.,  65,  111.     Psychologie,  pp.  266-71,  499,  500. 
2  Pp.  499,  500. 


GENESIS  OF  INDIVIDUALITY.  149 

virtue  of  their  very  variety.  But  if,  now,  individuation  thus 
runs  through  the  whole  essence  of  humanity,  in  what  way  is 
the  divine  will  concerning  individuality  realized  ?  And  what 
are  its  principal  sorts  ? 

§  14.   The  actual  Genesis  of  the  chief  kinds  of  Individuality. 

In  inquiring  after  the  origin  of  the  multitude  of  possible 
individualities,  it  is  to  considered — A.  That  germs  for 
the  production  of  various  peculiarities  of  human  nature 
are  found  even  in  one  and  the  same  individual,  namely, 
in  the  necessary  variety  of  his  moods  at  different  times 
(§  11.  7).  B.  But  the  possible  individualizations  of 
human  nature  come  to  full  expression  only  in  different 
persons ;  and  here  are  to  be  distinguished :  1.  The 
differences  which  relate  to  condition ;  and  2.  Those 
which  relate  to  activity.  1.  To  condition  belong:  a. 
The  difference  of  sex,  this  original  differentiation  or 
individualization  of  human  nature.  I.  From  this  results, 
in  connection  with  the  difference  of  physico-psychical 
moods,  the  difference  of  temperaments,  which  express  a 
fundamental  mood  permanently  held,  and,  as  it  were, 
impersonated,  c.  From  the  varieties  of  this  permanent 
fundamental  mood,  different  races,  7iations,  i^eoples,  tribes 
may  be  derived.  But  there  are  also,  2.  Peculiarities 
which  relate  to  activity;  these  are  the  tcdents,  which 
form  the  basis  for  individual  vocations. 

Note. — We  have,  moreover,  to  distinguish  between  differences 
wliich  are  or  should  be  transient  (of  age,  of  good  and  bad),  and 
those  permanent  differences  of  definite  individuals,  the  germ 
of  which  becomes  only  more  strongly  developed  by  education. 

1.  The  realm  of  diversity  is  indeed  immeasurable,  and 
human  science  cannot  boast  of  having  made  a  general  survey 
of  it,  much  less  of  having  studied  out  the  wisdom  of  the 
Creator  as  it  extends  down  to  single  individuals.  Yet  we 
must  seek  to  outline,  so  far  as  we  may,  the  realm  of  indi- 
vidualities, in  order  that  we  may  come  to  know  the  factors 


150  §  14.    GENESIS  OF  INDIVIDUALITY. 

■which  make  so  great  a  diversity  possible,  and  in  order  that 
we  may  be  able  to  regulate  this  diversity  in  a  rational  way. 
These  factors  are,  as  it  were,  the  alphabet,  out  of  which  the 
creative  thought  of  God  composes  as  many  independent  words 
as  there  are  individuals.  But  at  the  same  time  we  must 
disregard  that  kind  of  diversity  which  ought  not  to  exist, 
which  has  arisen  through  mere  abnormity  and  sin,  and  which 
tends  to  destruction,  that  is,  to  the  uniformity  of  death. 
Furthermore,  to  the  diversity  of  the  human  race,  as  it  con- 
stantly exists,  an  immense  deal  is  contributed  by  the  mingling 
of  classes  of  persons  of  the  most  different  ages  who  are  living 
at  the  same  time.  One  and  the  same  person  thinks,  feels, 
and  acts  otherwise  in  childhood  than  in  youth  or  in  manhood. 
But  inasmuch  as  the  child  becomes  the  boy,  the  boy  the  youth, 
etc.,  the  differences  of  age  mark  only  different  stages  of  one 
and  the  same  being.  But  this  diversity  forms  in  itself  no 
ground  of  difference  of  individuality.  The  several  periods  of 
life  constitute  only  distinctions  which  every  one  as  he  advances 
in  years  goes  beyond,  which  therefore  form  no  essential  dis- 
tinction, but  rather  are  involved  in  that  earthly  self-reproduc- 
tion of  the  individual  which  belongs  to  the  essence  of  a  living 
being. 

The  self-reproduction,  which  in  this  aspect  of  it  establishes 
no  permanent  distinction,  is,  however,  in  another  aspect,  that 
is,  as  the  reproduction  of  the  species,  the  foundation  of  a  real 
individuality  of  a  permanent  kind,  viz.  the  difference  of  sex. 
Then  again,  perhaps  this  self-reproduction,  in  connection  with 
the  necessary  change  of  moods,  furnishes  a  clue  for  under- 
standing the  differences  of  other  individuations.  Having 
eliminated  evil  and  difference  of  age  from  among  the  sources 
of  individuality,  we  are  to  consider  two  main  kinds  of  factors 
of  individuality :  (1)  The  difference  of  temperament  and  of 
race — men  considered  as  wlioles,  as  existing  in  a  certain 
state ;  (2)  the  difference  of  talents  —  men  considered  as 
active,  as  tending  to  produce.  These  two  main  kinds  of  indi- 
viduality must  always  be  in  some  way  blended,  since  each 
person  is  also  made  for  action,  so  that,  from  this  connection 
of  different  modifications  of  condition  with  modifications  of 
action,  new  grounds  of  individuation  again  result. 

2.  Difference  of  sex. — The  species,  which  as  such  nowhere 


DIFFERENCE  OF  SEX.       THE  MASCULINE  NATURE.  151 

appears  by  itself,  exists  only  in  the  duality  of  sex  ;  the  species 
differentiates  itself  into  this  duality,  in  order  to  reproduce 
itself  in  new  individuals.  But  just  this  differentiation  draws 
the  two  sexes  together  again ;  both  seek  each  other,  in  order 
to  find  their  complement  in  each  other,  and  out  of  the  differ- 
ence to  reach  the  point  of  exhibiting  the  species  as  a  unity 
and  as  a  totality.  And  thereby  they  become  the  instruments 
of  tlie  self-reproducing  species.^  The  one  human  life  divides 
into  two  poles,  strength  and  Icauty ;  with  the  one,  through  a 
moral  process,  there  comes  to  be  connected  ethical  dignity, 
with  the  other,  ethical  grace.  But  this  difference  is  by  no 
means  merely  physical,  it  extends  even  into  the  mental  nature 
of  mankind ;  for  Christ  by  no  means  says  ^  that  this  difference 
will  be  utterly  obliterated,  but  only  that  the  conditions  of 
marrying  and  being  given  in  marriage,  of  this  earthly,  physical 
marking  of  the  difference  of  sex,  will  be  removed. 

The  essential  characteristic  of  the  mascidine  nature  as  such 
consists  in  courage,  which  guards  and  keeps  the  honour  of  his 
independence  with  all  physical  and  intellectual  means,  and 
determines  the  whole  natural  peculiarity  of  the  man  as  such. 
To  the  masculine  nature,  however,  belongs  not  merely 
courageous  self-assertion,  but  also  aggressiveness.  Man  copes 
with  the  outward  world ;  and  this  places  him  in  advance  of 
woman  in  the  world  of  luill  which  aims  at  action.  But  also  on 
the  side  of  cognition  his  nature  operates  in  such  a  manner  that, 
instead  of  dwelling  in  himself  in  immediate  self-consciousness, 
or  giving  himself  up  to  contemplation,  he  sets  himself  more 
distinctly  over  against  liimself,  and  thereby  over  against  the 
world.  Reflection  is  more  peculiar  to  the  man ;  therefore 
there  is  in  him  greater  clearness  of  self-consciousness  ;  he 
views  himself  more  objectively,  and  also  the  world  as  it  objec- 
tively is  in  itself,  and  not  only  as  it  affects  him  individually. 
Finally,  the  same  thing  is  to  be  seen  even  on  the  side  of 
feeling.  Tor  the  mascidine  nature  reacts  more  in  the  form  of 
deed  against  modification  from  without,  and  especially  against 
suffering ;  feeling  in  the  man  passes  over  more  into  a  thought- 
picture,  which  makes  definite  the  object  of  feeling,  whether  it 
be  pleasant  or  unpleasant,  and  which,  connected  with  the 
conscious  feeling  of  value,  excites  the  impulse  to  produce  or 
1  Gen.  ii.  23,  24.  -  Matt.  xx.  30. 


152  §  14.    GENESIS  OF  INDIVIDUALITY. 

to  act.  The  feminine  nature,  on  the  other  hand,  dwells  more 
in  the  feeling  itself,  floating  in  the  sense  either  of  pleasure  or 
of  displeasure,  opposing  to  that  which  causes  suffering  or  dis- 
pleasure the  feminine  bravery,  which  consists  in  endurance. 
Passive  devotion  is  not  contrary  to  the  feminine  nature.  This 
nature  is  not  determined  so  much  by  reasons  as  by  impulses 
(§  11.  3).  But  the  man  should  have  reasons  as  well  as 
impulses.  Sentimentality  and  mere  passiveness  in  becoming 
conscious  or  in  being  influenced  are  unmanly ;  they  are  even 
a  degenerate  form  of  feminineness,  i.e.  effeminate. 

The  fundamental  characteristic  of  vjoman,  in  contrast  with 
the  masculine  spontaneousness  and  capacity  for  production,  is 
rather  receptiveness,  which,  however,  is  very  different  from 
passiveness.  Since  in  the  feminine  nature  subjectiveness  pre- 
dominates, the  woman  dwells  more  in  her  undivided  being, 
whereas  the  man  enters  far  more  into  the  several  functions  of 
willing,  reflecting,  or  thinking,  nay,  as  it  were,  for  the  moment 
is  merged  in  them.  There  are,  to  be  sure,  in  the  feminine 
nature  also  those  differences  of  the  mental  faculties  with  their 
different  functions;  but  they  come  only  in  the  masculine  nature 
to  distinct  manifestation,  and  thereby  to  full  reality.  But  as 
the  woman  is  not  in  herself  so  divided  as  the  man,  so  she  does 
not  recognise  the  distinctions  in  herself,  nor  does  the  outward 
world  stand  so  objectively  before  her.  Woman's  ideality  is  far 
more  intimately  connected  with  her  reality,  i.e.  her  body  and 
her  world,  than  that  of  man  is ;  for  which  reason  the  develop- 
ment of  the  man  has  far  more  to  do  with  opposites,  whereas 
the  w^oman,  both  in  good  and  in  evil,  dwells  more  in  the  con- 
centrated unity  of  her  nature.  Since  beauty  is  nothing  else 
than  spirit  and  soul  appearing  in  bodily  form,  and  since  the 
woman  keeps  the  body  in  far  more  immediate  union  with  the 
spirit,  the  soul  in  her  shines  more  immediately  through ;  and 
so  the  female  sex  exhibits  human  life  on  the  side  of  heauty. 
The  more  woman  is  in  herself  an  expression  of  simple, 
spontaneous  harmony,  and  the  more  she  has  the  impulse  to 
make  the  outward  world  share  in  her  self-manifestation ;  so 
much  the  more  does  she  cultivate  beauty  outside  of  herself,  so 
much  the  more  importance  does  she  attach  to  the  outward,  in 
order  that  it  may  not  disturb  the  harmony,  but  that  the  out- 
ward may  correspond  to  the  conception  which  the  soul  has  of 


THE  FEMININE  NATURE.  153 

itself.  Not  till  the  outward  world  is  severed  from  tlie  inward, 
not  till  the  appearance  tends  to  assume  importance  indepen- 
dently of  the  soul,  does  the  fault  begin,  to  which  the  feminine 
nature  is  especially  exposed,  namely,  the  fault  of  vanity,  or 
further  on,  that  of  dissimulation. 

The  concentrated  unity  of  the  feminine  nature  gives  to 
women  especially  the  vocation  of  being  the  bearing  sex  ;  in 
devotion,  in  self-sacrifice,  the  genuine  feminine  nature  finds 
its  blessedness.  Nothing  has  power  so  to  spread  peace 
over  a  household  as  maternal  love  and  its  benign,  sustaining 
sway ;  while  the  virtue  of  man  is  rather  that  of  producing, 
providing,  and  ruling.  The  same  concentrated  unity,  however, 
is  also  the  cause  of  the  easy  vulnerability  and  delicacy  of  the 
feminine  nature ;  injured  in  one  part,  it  feels  itself  injured 
throughout ;  for  the  soul  predominates,  and  the  whole  nature 
is,  as  it  were,  present  in  every  point.  The  same  unity  of 
nature  accounts  for  the  fact,  further,  that  the  chastity,  modesty, 
and  maidenly  pride  which  protect  maidenly  honour  with 
the  whole  strength  of  noble  self-regard,  are  in  woman  a 
sort  of  natural  endowment,  identical  with  self-preservation. 
Tor  with  the  loss  of  feminine  honour  the  whole  individuality 
of  woman  is  degraded,  as  is  the  case  with  man  when  he  loses 
his  honour  in  another  direction. 

If  we  turn  now  in  particular  to  the  intellectual  side,  the 
woman  is  constitutionally  more  inclined  to  religion,  the  man 
to  morality ;  the  woman  is  more  fitted  for  attachment,  the  man 
more  for  independence ;  the  woman  has  more  of  the  poetry  of 
the  feelings,  the  lyrical  element,  the  man  rather  has  a  calling 
for  more  objective  poetry,  as  the  epic  and  dramatic.  The 
feminine  understanding  and  the  feminine  judgment,  more- 
over, are  of  a  wholly  different  kind  from  the  masculine ;  the 
woman  judges  by  a  sort  of  tact  with  the  understanding  of  the 
feelings,  yet  without  confounding  different  things ;  often  the 
woman  sees  through  what  is  foreign  to  her  far  more  quickly  than 
the  more  conscious  masculine  understanding  which  gives  its 
reasons.  For  general  impressions  determine  her  judgment ; 
from  a  general  impression  the  whole  nature  of  the  woman,  so 
to  speak,  answers  a  question  directed  to  her  concerning  a 
definite  relation.  It  might  be  thought  that,  according  to  this, 
the  judgment  and  understanding  of  woman,  although,  as  is 


154  §  14.    GENESIS  OF  INDIVIDUALITY. 

well  known,  she  does  not  like  to  deal  with  reasons,  must  be 
more  circumspect  and  considerate  than  man's,  must  take  into 
view  more  the  totality  of  relations.  But  however  decided  the 
feminine  judgment  is  wont  to  be,  especially  as  woman  is  more 
emotional  than  man,  it  is  yet  to  be  noticed  that  she  judges  as 
her  fcclmg  directs,  which,  although  intellectual,  is  yet  subjec- 
tive ;  and  the  thorough  culture  of  that,  therefore,  is  the  urgent 
thing. 

This  leads  us  to  the  volitional  side  of  woman's  nature.  She 
is,  to  be  sure,  perfectly  equipped  for  those  spheres  in  which 
the  whole  person,  as  a  unit,  comes  into  view ;  and  there 
she  is  capable  of  a  sound  judgment.  To  those  spheres 
belong  the  two  extremes  of  the  ethical  community,  viz.  the 
family  and  the  Church,  in  which  the  totality  of  the  person 
comes  to  view  ;  for  active  life  in  these  spheres  requires  the 
devotion  of  the  whole  person.  But  between  these  limits  lie 
friendship,  the  State,  art,  and  science  ;  all  these  spheres  and 
their  culture  require  a  far  more  objective  consciousness  and 
self-consciousness  than  is  peculiar  to  woman.  They  are  in  them- 
selves one-sided  spheres  ;  and  hence  the  feminine  nature  has 
little  judgment  and  aptitude  for  them,  is  continually  inclined 
to  apply  to  them  a  foreign  standard  (especially  to  the  State 
and  to  science),  and  so  is  not  endowed  in  such  a  way  as  to  be 
productively  active  in  them.  And  in  this  matter  women's 
universities  and  attempts  at  the  so-called  emancipation  of 
women  will  not  alter  anything,  but  will  only  attain  the  result 
that  women  will  seem  less  amiable  to  us  men,  at  least  so  far 
forth  as  we  are  not  so  selfish  and  vain  as  highly  to  esteem 
only  that  for  which  we  have  special  aptitude  and  skill.  On 
the  other  hand,  woman  is  admirably  endowed  for  guarding  the 
masculine  nature  and  the  spheres  especially  entrusted  to  it 
from  such  one-sidednesses  as  are  inconsistent  with  a  compre- 
hensive spirit  and  with  harmonious  unity.  For  women,  over 
against  all  such  one-sidednesses,  into  which  the  masculine 
nature  is  apt  to  fall,  represent  universal  human  nature. 

This  difference  of  the  two  sexes  is  at  the  outset  unconscious, 
although  present  as  a  fact.  Children  of  both  sexes  play 
together.  But  later  there  must  follow,  where  the  development 
is  normal,  a  period  of  estrangement  between  two  sexes,  coin- 
ciding with  the  coming  on  of  puberty.     At  this  period  each 


THE  TEMPEEAMENTS.       LITERATURE.  155 

sex  comes  to  a  consciousness  of  its  own  peculiarity,  and  consoli- 
dates itself  therein ;  and  the  creative  will  which  has  ordained  the 
difference  of  sex  is  not  perfectly  realized  except  through  this 
estrangement.  But  since  the  duality  of  the  sexes  cannot  be 
an  ultimate  end,  this  separation  and  estrangement  only  serves 
to  intensify  the  antecedent  conditions  of  a  union  v/hich  is  all 
the  more  intimate.     But  of  this  we  treat  in  the  next  section. 


§  14:h. — Continuation. 

3.   The  Temperaments. 

Literature. — Alexander  von  Humboldt, /rcsmas.  [Cosmos: 
Sketch  of  a  Physieal  Deservption  of  the  Universe.  Translation  by 
A.  Prichard,  begun  1845,  also  by  E.  Sabine,  1846. — Tr.]  Daub, 
Moral,  ii.  1,  pp.  144-49.  Wirth,  Fhilosojjhische  Uthilc,  ii.  22  sq. 
Haug,  AUgeraeine  Geschichtc,  Heft  1,  p.  08  sq.  Also,  the 
Anthrop)ologie  of  Kant,  Burdach,  Waitz.  Werner,  Christliche 
EthiJc,  i.  161.  Eambach,  Die  christliche  Sittenlchre,  2nd  ed. 
1738,  chap.  viii.  p.  680  sq.  Eambach  recognises  only  three 
temperaments  ;  the  melancholic  supplies,  according  to  him, 
also  the  place  of  the  phlegmatic.  From  innate  qualities  of  the 
soul  he,  like  Stahl,  derives  the  qualities  of  the  body.  Daub 
distinguishes  the  temperaments  according  to  the  elements, 
water  (phlegma),  air  (sanguine  T.),  fire  (choleric  T.) ;  tlie 
melancholic  is  disease.  On  the  other  hand,  he  says,  there 
might  be  laid  down,  as  a  fourth,  the  terrestrial  temperament, 
the  boorish  or  Boeotian,  which,  living  from  the  soil  {humus), 
has  humour,  wit,  and  understanding ;  this,  according  to  him, 
is  the  Germanic  temperament.  Jlirgen  Bona  Mayer,  Philo- 
sophische  Zeitfragen,  1870,  p.  185  sqq.,  distinguishes  light  or 
heavy  (quick  or  slow),  and  also  strong  or  weak,  mobility  of 
feeling  and  of  will ;  slowness  and  weakness  of  sensation,  he 
says,  belong  to  the  phlegmatic ;  quickness  and  intensive 
strength  to  the  choleric  ;  slowness  joined,  however,  with  strong 
susceptibility,  to  the  melancholic  ;  quickness,  joined  with 
weaker  intensity  of  feeling  and  will,  to  the  sanguine  ;  but  each 
of  the  two,  sensibility  and  will,  may  be  either  slow  or  quick, 
strong  or  weak,  that  is,  each  differing  in  a  fourfold  way,  whence 
new  varieties  result.  Eothe,  i.  §  128  sqq.,  2nd  ed.,  finds  the 
original  seat  of  the  temperaments  in  the  material  side  of  man, — 
in  sensation  and  impulse,  which  precede  the  personal  life, 
wherein  they  become  feeling  and  desire,  i.e.  begin  to  have 
an  object.  He  distinguishes  the  temperaments  into  two  pairs : 
first,  those  marked  by  the  understanding,  as  excitable  or  com- 


156  §  lib.    THE  TEMPEKAMENTS.       DIFFERENT  VIEWS. 

posed  (sanguine  and  melancholic  temperaments) ;  secondly,  by 
the  will  in  like  contrast  (choleric  and  phlegmatic  temperaments). 
According  to  Eothe,  these  two  pairs  exclude  each  other ;  yet 
he  concedes  that  there  are  also  mixed  temperaments,  and  that 
their  right  management  by  the  person  is  possible  (§  131,  165, 
174).  As  faults  he  designates  (§  215,  131),  on  the  side  of 
the  understanding,  disproportionately  weak  receptivity  (dul- 
ness),  disproportionately  strong  excitability  (frivolity,  giddi- 
ness) ;  on  the  side  of  the  will,  disproportionately  weak  spon- 
taneousness  (inertness),  disproportionately  strong  excitability 
(hastiness,  passionateness).  Schleiermacher  also  goes  back 
to  receptiveness  and  spontaneousness,  qxuckness  and  slowness 
of  emotions,  as  the  basis  of  the  distinction  of  the  tem- 
peraments. Striimpell,  on  the  other  hand  (Vorschide  dcr 
2)hiloso2:)h.  Ethih,  p.  138  sq.),  who  finds  the  grounds  of 
individuality  in  the  psychical  and  corporeal  nature,  and  their 
action  on  each  other,  sees  the  psychical  cause  of  differences  in 
the  quality  of  the  mental  imirrcssions,  on  which  again  the 
feelings  and  desires  depend.  But  also  the  quantity  of  the 
impressions  and  thoughts,  their  scope  and  their  strength,  are  to 
be  considered,  and,  moreover,  the  manner  of  combining  the 
thoughts  in  series,  their  connection  and  their  arrangement, 
and  the  interpenetration  and  compactness  of  the  groups  of 
impressions.  The  defect,  with  Striimpell,  lies  in  the  fact  that 
he  derives  the  differences  of  individualities  only  from  outward 
influences,  and  consequently  treats  individuality  in  its  psychical 
centre  only  as  receptivity.  Lotze  finally,  in  his  Mikrokosmus, 
ii.  352  sq.  [English  tr.  vol.  ii.  pp.  26-39.— Te.],  is  inclined  to 
trace  back  the  temperaments  to  the  four  periods  of  life.  [In 
his  Grundzuge  der  Psi/clwlor/ie,  on  the  other  hand,  pp.  82,  83, 
he  understands  by  temperaments  nothing  more  than  the  formal 
and  gradual  differences  in  susceptibility  to  outward  impressions  ; 
in  the  extent  to  which  impressions  when  excited  reproduce 
others ;  in  rapidity  in  the  change  of  impressions ;  in  the 
strength  with  whicli  feelings  of  pleasure  and  of  displeasure 
connect  themselves  with  the  impressions  ;  and  in  the  ease  with 
which  outward  actions  connect  themselves  with  the  inward 
states.  The  temperaments,  in  his  view,  are  various  beyond 
measure  ;  but  the  most  definite  types  are  the  four  well-known 
ones  :  the  sanguine,  with  great  rapidity  of  change  and  lively 
excitability;  the  phlegmatic,  with  little  versatility  and  slow 
reactions  ;  the  choleric,  one-sidedly  susceptible,  with  great 
energy  in  single  directions;  the  sentimental,  sensitive  to  the 
value  which  all  possible  relations  have  to  the  feelings,  but 
indifferent  towards  mere  facts. — Ed.] 

Temperament    denotes    the    physical,    i.e.     corporeal     and 


THE  FOUR  TEMPEKAMENTS.  157 

psychical,  fundamental  mood ;  the  original  and  peculiar 
constitution  of  the  sensibilities  in  themselves  and  in  their 
relation  to  the  objective  world.  From  of  old  it  has  been 
customary  to  enumerate  four  temperaments ;  and  little  as 
this  number  has  been  construed  as  necessary,  yet  the  great 
unanimity  in  the  matter  is  remarkable,  and  indicates  that  it 
has  been  gathered  from  fact.  Although  the  temperaments 
may  in  fact  no  longer  be  frequently  found  pure,  but  rather 
almost  always  mixed,  yet  that  does  not  hinder  us  from 
detecting  by  analysis  the  four  fundamental  forms,  which  lie 
at  the  basis  of  the  mixed  temperaments  also.  These  four 
are  the  phlegmatic  and  the  sanguine,  the  melancholic  and 
the  choleric.-^ 

If  we  describe  these  four,  first,  according  to  their  corporeal 
aspect,  then,  as  has  been  conjectured,  in  the  phlegmatic  the 
vegetative  lymphatic  system  dominates  ;  in  the  choleric,  the 
arterial  system ;  in  the  melancholic,  the  venous  system ;  in 
the  sanguine,  the  nervous  system.  But  the  difference  in  the 
habitual  fundamental  mood  is  so  deep  that  we  need  to  adduce 
also  ihe  psychical  element.  And  so  we  must  say  that,  even 
irrespective  of  sin,  four  different  moods  are  possible  in  human 
nature,  into  each  of  which,  at  least  for  the  moment,  every 
individual  may,  and  in  the  course  of  his  life  must,  pass,  so 
that  all  temperaments  are  found  in  all  persons.  But,  on  the 
other  hand,  these  can  also  become  habitual  and  permanent  in 
such  a  way  that  one  of  them  is  the  predominant  one,  that  is, 
forms  always  the  point  of  departure  for  the  transition  into 
others,  and  hence  in  them  also  continues  to  operate ;  as,  e.g., 
the  anger  of  a  phlegmatic  man  is  of  a  quite  different  sort 
from  that  of  the  choleric  or  of  the  sanguine  man ;  and  the 
sorrow  or  joy  of  the  sanguine  man  is  of  a  different  sort  from 
that  of  the  melancholic  man  ;  and  none  the  less,  too,  the  taking 
up  and  treatment  of  the  same  task  will  be  very  different  in 
different  temperaments.  And  as  each  person  sets  out  from 
the  fundamental  mood  as  the  foundation,  so  there  will  always 

^  These  four  may  be  illustrated  by  a  figure  like  a  Greek  cross,  having 
four  arms  ;  they  form,  as  it  were,  two  axes  cutting  each  other  at  right  angles  ; 
the  two  poles  of  each  axis  form  a  direct  opposite  to  each  other,  the  choleric 
opposite  to  the  phlegmatic,  the  melancholic  opposite  to  the  sanguine.  Between 
the  poles  of  each  of  the  two  axes,  the  poles  of  the  other  axis  form  an  inter- 
mediate. 


158        §  Uh.    THE  TEMPEKAMENTS,      THE  PHLEGMATIC,  SANGUINE, 

be  an  inclination  to  return  into  it.  ISTow  the  particular 
natural  fundamental  mood,  thus  maintained,  we  call  the 
temperament. 

This  habitual  mood  may  be,  in  the  first  place,  that  of  repose 
and  stability,  which  has  the  natural  tendency  to  preserve  the 
equilibrium  between  the  outward  and  the  inward  with  reference 
to  immediate  consciousness,  and  to  exercise  patient  endurance 
in  doing  and  suffering.  The  phlegmatic  temperament,  which 
we  have  thus  described,  is  not  a  favourite ;  one  does  not  like 
to  possess  it.  But  as  to  the  names  of  the  temperaments,  we 
must  not  forget  that  these  are  taken  from  an  experience 
which  already  shows  connected  with  the  temperament  some- 
thing abnormal,  not  belonging  to  the  essence  of  it.  In  itself 
considered,  that  which  we  have  designated  as  the  phlegmatic 
temperament,  is  not  more  one-sided  than  any  other,  but  is  to 
be  designated,  according  to  its  strict  idea,  as  the  temperament 
of  continuity  in  itself  or  of  identity  with  itself.  It  repre- 
sents an  element,  therefore,  which,  remaining  one-sided,  and 
coming  too  soon  to  permanent  sway,  hinders  progress,  but 
which,  on  the  other  hand,  not  only  must  present  itself  to  the 
mind  as  an  end  to  be  aimed  at,  but  is  also  the  natural 
starting-point  for  development.  In  this  development  itself, 
however,  it  represents  an  element  without  which  no  progress 
would  be  possible,  but,  at  the  most,  empty  motion  in  a  circle. 
This  element  is  stalility,  the  assertion  of  the  identity  of  the 
person  with  himself  in  doing  and  suffering,  in  taking  in  and 
giving  out. 

A  second  habitual  fundamental  mood  or  temperament  is 
the  sanguine,  an  open,  buoyant,  and  self- surrendering  sus- 
ceptibility, a  state  of  natural  connection  with  the  objective 
world, — a  state  in  which  one  is  easily  moved  to  joy  or  to 
sorrow  by  outward  things.  In  cognition  it  manifests  itself  as 
a  restless  thirst  for  knowledge ;  in  will,  as  an  impulse  to  form 
ideals;  in  feeling,  as  social  excitability,  quickness  of  appre- 
hension, and  love  of  change ;  but  oftentimes  also  in  volatility, 
moodiness,  and  fickleness. 

By  the  side  of  these  two  temperaments,  however,  two  more 
are  possible.  The  third  temperament  is  characterized  by  a 
tendency  to  subjectiveness,  to  abstraction  from  the  outward 
world,  to  retirement  into  one's  self  ;  this  is  the  melancholic ; 


MELANCHOLIC,  AND  CHOLERIC.  159 

while  the  fourth,  the  choleric,  is  radically  inclined  to  go  forth 
out  of  itself,  reacting  against  the  outward  world  and  moulding 
it.  As  the  two  temperaments  first  mentioned  manifest  them- 
selves, in  all  the  main  directions  of  mental  activity,  differently 
in  the  different  sexes  and  at  different  periods  of  life,  so  the 
same  is  true  of  this  second  pair. 

For  the  melancholic  temperament  shows  itself  not  only  in 
feeling,  but  also  in  the  world  of  thought  and  of  will.  In 
feeling  it  inclines  one  to  solitary  withdrawal  into  one's  self, 
and,  with  reference  to  religion,  to  mysticism.  In  thought 
it  is  indicated  by  a  tendency  to  profoundness,  inwardness, 
and  speculative  occupation.  In  the  realm  of  the  will  it 
involves  such  a  dissatisfaction  with  previous  things  as  is 
favourable  to  progress,  and  involves  also  the  critical  talent, 
and  abstraction  from  the  solid  world  of  present  reality.  But 
it  may  incline  to  pessimism,  just  as  the  sanguine  temperament 
to  optimism.  If  the  melancholic  man  should  stop  short  with 
this  abstraction  instead  of  advancing  to  action,  he  would,  as 
it  were,  relapse  into  that  which  is  the  degeneration  of  the 
phlegmatic  temperament,  against  which,  nevertheless,  the 
melancholic,  by  the  critical  element  inherent  in  it,  is  fitted  to 
guard  him.  It  would  become  in  that  case  desponding 
resignation,  just  because  it  is  deficient  in  that  which  is  the 
true  characteristic  of  the  phlegmatic  temperament,  namely, 
repose  in  one's  self,  comparative  satisfaction  and  security  of 
mind. 

Finally,  the  choleric,  drastic,  the  temperament  of  active 
opposition  to  the  imperfection  of  things,  the  impulse  to  shape 
the  world  courageously  and  energetically  according  to  a  set 
purpose,  runs  through  all  the  faculties  of  the  soul.  To  feeling 
this  temperament  lends  fervour,  with  a  tendency  to  passion, 
not  to  the  aesthetic  passion  of  enjoyment  as  in  the  case  of  the 
sanguine  person,  but  to  the  practical  passion,  or  the  passion 
for  action.  In  the  moral  sphere  this  fervour  becomes 
enthusiasm.  To  thought  the  choleric  temperament  lends  the 
energy  for  creating  and  shaping  the  ideal  in  art  or  science. 
To  the  will,  finally,  it  lends  the  two?,  the  elasticity,  which 
copes  with  the  outward  world.  Thus  the  choleric  and 
melancholic  temperaments  seem  to  be  able  to  show  them- 
selves in  perfection  in  the  masculine  nature ;  the  other  two 


160  §  Uh.    THE  TEMPERAMENTS.       UNION  OF  THEM. 

more  in  the  feminine  nature.  In  the  melancholic  and 
choleric  temperaments  spontaneous  activity  prevails,  in  the 
former  inward,  in  the  latter  outward,  activity ;  while 
excitability  of  the  psychical  life  is  characteristic  of  the 
sanguine  man,  but  in  the  case  of  the  phlegmatic  is  less 
prominent. 

However  different  or  even  opposed  may  be  the  temperament 
of  abstraction,  and  that  of  connection  with  the  outward  world 
(the  melancholic  and  the  sanguine),  or,  on  the  other  hand, 
that  of  stability  and  sameness,  and  that  of  restless  progress 
(the  phlegmatic  and  the  choleric),  yet  it  cannot  be  said  that 
the  excellences  which  each  of  the  temperaments  represents 
exclude  each  other.  For  that  would  bring  a  contradiction 
into  the  moral  constitution.  Eather,  transitions  from  the 
peculiarities  of  one  to  those  of  another  are  possible  and 
actual ;  partly  involuntary,  through  change  of  moods  in  the 
same  person  and  through  difference  of  age,  partly  produced  by 
the  will  and  moral  self-culture.  For  they  do  not  exist  for  the 
sake  of  fortifying  themselves  against  each  other.  Each, 
without  elements  of  the  others,  makes  a  one-sided,  imperfect 
person ;  therefore  a  blending  of  them  needs  to  be  brought 
about.  As  that  which  is  one-sided  and  divisive  in  the 
difference  of  the  sexes  can  and  should  be  overcome,  so  far  as 
mind  is  concerned,  each  individual  in  his  moral  development 
appropriating  to  himself  the  mental  excellences  of  the  other 
sex  which  do  not  by  nature  belong  to  him,  so  the  same  holds 
good  also  of  the  temperaments.^ 

To  this  process  of  mutual  permeation  nature  itself  points 
in  its  normal  course.  For,  physically  considered,  childhood 
presents  more  the  vegetative  life  in  identity  with  itself ;  in 
boyhood  and  youth  the  sanguine  temperament  has  its  natural 
beginnings ;  in  manhood  there  is  generally  seen  in  every  one 
somewhat  of  the  choleric ;  in  old  age,  the  time  of  involution, 
generally  somewhat  of  the  temperament  of  abstraction.     But 

1  Rotlie,  I.e.  2nd  ed.  §  219.  After  showing  tliat  the  affections  take  different 
forms  according  to  the  temperament,  the  melancholic  inclining  to  fear,  the 
choleric  to  passionateness,  the  sangnine  to  rash  hope,  the  phlegmatic  to 
indolence,  he  says  (§  220)  that  as  affections  of  the  temperament,  fear  and 
passionateness  are  conquerable,  and  so  are  transformed  into  reserve  and 
indignation,  in  which  case  they  have  laid  aside  the  involuntary  element  in 
them. 


THEIR  RELATION  TO  MORALITY.  161 

this  blending,  in  order  to  be  of  a  moral  character,  must  be 
accomplished  consciously  by  the  will  and  by  continued  self- 
culture,  so  that,  e.g.,  age  does  not  need  to  lose  mental  youth. 
Uniformity  ought  not  to  be  aimed  at  by  this  blending  of  tem- 
peraments ;  the  diversity  arising  from  differences  in  strength, 
in  liveliness,  and  in  the  mingling  of  elements  still  remains; 
also  the  original  difference  continues  to  operate.  For  that 
diversity  conditions  the  order  in  the  succession  of  the  elements 
of  a  normal  combination,  and  also  the  goal  to  be  aimed  at ; 
and  that  difference  of  order  involves  also  the  overcoming 
of  corresponding  temptations.  Each  of  the  temperaments,  to 
start  with,  has  a  natural  tendency  to  excellences:  the  sanguine, 
to  kindliness,  courtesy,  joyousness,  pleasure  in  the  ideal ;  the 
melancholic,  to  seriousness  and  self-concentration ;  the  choleric, 
to  courage,  aspiration,  enthusiasm ;  the  phlegmatic,  to  equipoise 
and  repose.  But  each  of  them  has  also  a  natural  tendency  to 
faults  :  frivolousness  and  superficialness  threaten  the  sanguine  ; 
gloominess,  narrowness,  and  unsociableness,  the  melancholic ; 
passionateness,  pride,  ambition,  and  revenge,  the  choleric ; 
indolence,  coldness,  and  stupidity,  the  phlegmatic. 

From  the  foregoing  it  is  also  plain  why  only  a  few  indi- 
viduals exhibit  simply  and  one-sidedly  but  one  temperament. 
For,  as  already  said,  a  certain  combination  is  given  by  nature 
itself,  and  by  culture  also,  and  up  to  a  certain  extent  may 
be  hereditary.  By  this  concession  the  existence  of  funda- 
mental types  of  physical  and  psychical  nature,  which  are  the 
source  of  certain  fundamental  moods,  is  not  denied ;  but  by 
these  numerous  combinations,  which  may  also  reappear  in 
homogeneous  groups,  the  infinite  manifoldness  of  human 
nature  becomes  comprehensible.  Moreover,  it  is  to  be  insisted 
on,  that,  ethically  considered,  all  the  temperaments  are  equally 
good ;  none  is  sinful  in  itself,  although  each  by  itself  is  im- 
perfect. But  the  imperfections  of  each,  and  the  faults  con- 
nected with  them,  will  be  remedied  by  the  factors  of  the  others. 
The  temperaments  are  not  the  ground  of  any  natural  virtue 
by  reason  of  the  good  which  they  have  in  them ;  but  they 
also  excuse  no  sin  by  the  imperfections  which  they  involve. 
Since  the  difference  in  the  starting-point  for  moral  culture, 
and  the  difference  in  the  course  of  the  individual  life  there- 
with involved,  stamp  character  permanently,  and  thus  have 

L 


162  §  15.    THE  EACES  AND  NATIONALITIES. 

lasting  after-efiects,  we  must  not  go  so  far  as  to  say  ^  that 
moral  character  is  above,  that  is,  outside  of,  all  temperament. 
Character  is  in  the  temperament.  That  opinion  would  also 
not  be  in  agreement  with  the  fact  that  the  temperament  is  the 
appropriate  soil  in  which  the  spirit  is  to  develope  itself. 


§  15.  Continuation.      (Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  i.  §  43.) 
The  Races  and  Nationalities. 

[LiTERATUEE. — Blumeubach  and  Cuvier.  [J.  F.  Blumenbach, 
System  of  Comparative  Anatomy,  translated  from  the  German 
by  W.  Lawrence,  1807,  2nd  ed.  revised  and  enlarged,  under  the 
title,  Manual  of  Gom^parative  Anatomy,  by  W.  Coulson,  1827. 
The  Anthropological  Treatises  of  J.  F.  B.,  etc.,  translated  and 
edited  from  the  Latin,  German,  and  French  originals.  By 
T.  Bendyshe.  Anthropological  Society,  London  1863,  etc. 
Cuvier,  Lectures  on  Comparcctive  Anatomy,  translated  from 
French,  London  1802.  The  Animal  Kingdom,  etc.,  London 
1858. — Tr.]  'L^thnm,  Mccn  and  his  Migrations,  1851.  Darwin, 
The  Descent  of  Man,  2nd  ed.  1883.  The  Origin  of  Species, 
6th  ed.  1872.  Hiickel,  Natilrliche  Schopfungsgeschichte.  [In 
English  :  The  History  of  Creation,  London  1876. — Te.]  Anthro- 
pogenic. [In  English  :  The  Evolution  of  Man,  London  1879. — 
Te.]  Von  Hellwald,  Ctdturgeschichte.  Kriegk,  Die  Volher- 
stdmme  und,  Hire  Zwcige,  5th  ed.,  revised  by  Hellwald,  1883. 
Lubbock,  Tlie  Origin  of  Civilisation,  3rd  ed.  1875.  Huxley, 
Mans  Place  in  Nature,  1863.  Tylor,  Primitive  Culture,  1871. 
Researches  into  the  Early  History  of  ManJdnd,  etc.  [3rd  ed. 
1878.  Anthro2)ology,  London  1881. — Te.].  Wallace,  Ncdural 
Selection.  Owen,  Derivative  Hypothesis  of  Life  and  Species. 
J.  C.  Prichard,  The  Ncdural  History  of  Man  [4th  ed.  1855. 
Researches  into  the  Physical  History  of  ManJdnd,  3rd  ed., 
London  1836-47. — Te.].  Eatzel,  Vorgcschichte  des  europdisclien 
Menschen.  Lange,  Geschichte  des  McderiaLismiis,  2nd  ed.  [In 
English:  History  of  Mcdericdism.,  1877.— Te.]  Caspari,  Vor- 
gcschichte der  Mcnschhcit.  Burmeister,  Geschichte  der  Schop- 
fung,  7th  ed.  1872.  Fr.  Mueller,  Lehrhuch  der  allgemeinen 
Mhnogrctphie,  1S7S.  Peschel,  VolkerJcunde.  Glo^tz,  Speculative 
Theologie,  i.  1,  p.  200  sq.,  i.  2,  p.  772  sq. 

Eud.  Wagner,  Zoologisch-anthropologischc  Untersuchungen, 
1861.  Eiitimeyer,  Die  Grenzen  der  Thienvclt,  1867.  Virchow, 
Menschen  und  Affcnschddel,  1870.  [In  English  :  The  Cranial 
Affinities  of  Man  and  the  Ape,  1874.     In  Estes's  Hcdf-hour  Re- 

'  Wnttke,  Sittenlehre,  i.  387.     [Eng.  ed.  vol.  ii.  p.  72.— Tr.] 


WOEKS  ON  ANTHROPOLOGY.  163 

creations  in  Pojndar  Science,  Series  I. — Tr.]  Bcde  in  Wiesbaden, 
1873.  A.  W,  Volkmann,  Ueber  die  Enhcicklung  dcr  Organisrnen, 
1875.  Aeby,  Die  Schddelformen  der  Menschen  und  Affen,  1867. 
A.  V.  Humboldt,  Cosmos,  Schaller,  I.e.  p.  209  sq.  Eothe,  Ist 
ed.  i.  §  120,  p.  237,  regards  the  races  as  grades.  Waitz,  Ueler 
die  Einheit  des  Mcnsehengeschlechts  und  den  Urzustand  der 
Menschen,  oder  Anthropologic  der  Naturvolker.  Gerland, 
Anthropologisclie  Beitrdge.     Pfaff,  Schopfungsgeschichte,  2nd  ed. 

1877.  Die  Untstehimg  der  Welt  und  die  Naturgesetzc,  187*J. 
Quatrefages,  Unite  de  I'espece  humaine,  1861.  Theories  trans- 
formistes  ct  evolidionistcs.  Darwin  et  ses  precurseitrs  Francais, 
1870.  The  Human  Species,  1872.  Eudolf  Schmid,  Die  Dar- 
vnnisehen  TJieoriecn,  1876.  [In  English :  Theories  of  Darwin, 
etc.  Chicago  1883. — Tr.]  Lotze,  MikroJcosmos,  ii.  p.  99  sq. 
[1st  ed.,  3rd  ed.  p.  102  sq.  English  translation,  vol.  I.  Book  lY. 
chap.  V, — Tr.]  I.  H.  Fichte,  Anthropologic,  2nd  ed.  1860. 
Ulrici,  Gott  und  der  Mcnsch,  2nd  ed.  vol.  ii.  p.  146  sq. 
Zockler,  Ueber  die  Speziesfrage  in  ihrer  theologischen  Bedcutung, 
Jahrhucher  fur  deutsche  Theologie,  1861.  Heft  4,  pp.  659-714. 
Theologie  und  Naturwisscnschaft.  Die  Lehre  vom  Urstand,  1879. 
Wuttke,  i.  360  [English  ed.  vol.  ii.  p.  73  sq.— Tr.].  Agassiz, 
Schopfungsplan.  [^Structm'c  of  Animal  Life.  Six  Lectures 
delivered  in  1862,  3rd  ed.  1874. — Tr.]  Essay  on  Classification. 
[Essay  I.  of  Contributions  to  the  Natural  History  of  the  United 
States. — Tr.]  Hugh  Miller,  Footprints  of  the  Creator,  edited  by 
Agassiz,  1861.  Von  Baer,  Studien  aus  dem  Gebiete  der  Natur- 
toissenschaften,  1876.  Duke  of  Argyll,  Primeval  Man,  1869. 
Eeusch,  Bibel  unci  Ncdiir.  John  William  Dawson,  Nature  and 
the  Bible,  1875.  \_Fossil  Men  and  their  Modern  Repoxsentatives, 
2nd  ed.,  London  1883.  The  Story  of  the  Earth  and  Man,  8th 
ed.,  London  1883. — Tr.]  M'Cosh,  Christiaiiity  and  Positivism. 
His  paper  before  the  Evang.  Alliance,  1873,  and  in  Edinburgh, 

1878.  Huber,  Zur  Kritik  moderner  Sehopfungslehren,  1875. 
Erohschammer,  Ueber  die  Genesis  der  Menschheit  und  deren 
geistige  Entwickelung ,  etc.,  1883.  Al,  Braun,  Ueber  die  Bedcut- 
ung der  Entioiekelung  in  der  Naturgeschichte.  St.  G.  Mivart, 
Genesis  of  Species,  1871.  Ebrard,  Apologetik.  (Of.  likewise 
the  literature  above  given,  §  9.  3,  §  10,  and  System  of  Christian 
Doctrine,  i.  §  43.)     Erdmann,  Nationalitdtsprinzip,  1862. 

Comparative  Philology :  W.  v.  Humboldt,  Kawisprache,  1832. 
Sprachphilosophische  TVerke,  2  vols.  1883-84,  edited  by  Stein- 
thal.  Jacob  Grimm,  Ur sprung  der  Sprache,  1851.  Steinthal, 
Abriss  der  Sprachwissenschaft.  1  Thl.  Einlcitung  in  die 
Psychologic  und  Sprachwissensehaft,  2nd  ed.  1881.  Ursprung 
der  Sprache,  1858  [3rd  and  newly  -  revised  edition,  Berlin 
1877. — Tr.].     Charakteristik   der   hauptsctchlichsten   Typen  des 


164  §  15.    THE  EACES  AND  NATIONALITIES. 

Sprachhaues,  2nd  ed.  1860.  L.  Geiger,  Urs^orimfj  der  Sprache, 
1868-72.  August  Schleicher, -O-ie  Darivinische  Theoru  und  die 
Sprachvjissenschaft,  3rd  ed.  1873.  [Banvinism  tested  hy  the 
Science  of  Language,  translated  by  A.  V.  W.  Bikkers,  London 
1869.— Te.]  W.  Bleck,  Uclcr  den  Ursprung  der  Simichc,  1868. 
Ludwig  ISToire,  Ursprung  der  Sprache,  1877.  \_Max  Milller  and 
the  Ph  ilosopliy  of  Language.  Translated  from  the  German,  London 
1879 — Te.]  Fr.  Mueller,  Grundriss  der  allgemeincn  Spracli- 
uiisscnschaft,  1876.  Bastian,  Sprachvergleichende  Studien.  Max 
Mueller,  Ljccturcs  on  the  Science  of  Language,  1861-64.  New 
ed.  1880.  Wm.  D.  Whitney  [llie  Life  and  Growth  of  Language, 
1872.  Language  and  the  Study  of  LMnguage,  4th  ed.  1884. — Te.]. 
Oriental  and  Linguistic  Studies,  New  York  l773,  against 
Schleicher. — Editoe.] 

§  15. 

The  races  and  the  nationalities  seem  to  have  their  foundation 
in  the  differences  of  temperament,  in  connection  with 
the  influence  of  nature  and  of  history. 

1.  The  difference  of  races  and  of  nationalities  is  more 
difficult  of  treatment  than  the  temperaments ;  for  it  is  neces- 
sary, side  by  side  with  the  differences,  to  hold  fast  the  unity  of 
the  human  race,  and  correctly  to  define  this,  as  well  as  the 
differences.  The  Bible  gives  some  general  statements ;  it 
affirms  the  unity  of  mankind,  and  in  the  form  of  the  actual 
descent  of  all  from  Adam  (Eom.  v.  12  ;  1  Cor.  xv.  22  ;  Acts 
xvii.  26  ;  cf.  Gen.  i.).  The  peculiarities  then  spring  up  in  the 
case  of  the  three  brothers,  Shem,  Ham,  and  Japheth,  from 
whom  three  great  groups  of  races  descend  ;  and  further  in  the 
case  of  the  twelve  sons  of  Jacob  (Gen.  xlix.),  where  Jacob's 
blessing  indicates  the  peculiarities  of  the  sons,  and  glances  also 
at  the  peculiarities  of  the  tribes  springing  from  them. 

2.  Character  and  limit  of  the  differences  of  race  among  men. 
The  first  question  is,  whether  the  notion  of  kind  or  species 
is  applicable  to  the  differences  among  men  themselves,  or 
only  to  man  in  distinction  from  other  living  beings.  He 
who  assumes  the  unity  of  mankind,  that  is,  supposes  that 
mankind  as  a  whole  answers  to  the  notion  of  a  species  or 
genus,  allows  to  the  differences  among  men  only  the  signifi- 
cance of  derivatives  and  varieties  of  one  and  the  same  species, 
with  the  transmission,  indeed,  of  a  permanent  type.      He,  on 


THEORY  OF  DISTINCT  HUMAN  SPECIES.  165 

the  other  hand,  who  holds  the  races  to  be  original,  must 
designate  them  as  different  species  or  genera  of  men.  The 
unity,  further,  may  be  conceived  of  either  as  only  sameness 
of  nature,  sameness  of  the  hereditary  qualities,  or  also  as  a 
genealogical  unity.  The  differences  of  race  some  naturalists, 
as  Kant,  find  in  colour  ;  others,  as  Blumenbach  and  AVagner, 
in  the  form  of  the  skull ;  Hiickel,  Fr.  Miiller,  in  the  quality 
of  the  hair.  The  naturalists  differ  likewise  concerning  the 
number  of  the  races,  of  which  Blumenbach  assumes  five, 
Cuvier  and  Waitz  three,  Pickering  even  eleven,  others  still 
more.  But  the  question  which  chiefly  concerns  ethics  is, 
how  much  importance  is  assigned  to  the  soul  with  reference 
to  the  differences  of  race. 

(ft)  Some  naturalists  (and  a  short  time  ago  the  majority  of 
them)  have  thought  the  differences  in  the  human  family  so 
radical  that  they  have  felt  obliged  to  assume  the  races  to  be 
originally  different  human  genera.  The  lowest  of  the  races 
were  then  placed  about  on  a  parallel  with  the  highest  classes 
of  brutes.  This  would  involve  the  denial  not  only  of  the 
genealogical  unity  of  all  men  which  the  Bible  affirms,  and 
which  can  be  neither  proved  nor  disproved  by  natural  science, 
but  also  of  the  essential  unity  of  mankind,  which  might  be 
still  maintained  even  if  there  were  many  original  pairs, 
provided  only  that  all  had,  and  transmitted,  the  same  type.^ 
In  the  case  of  this  entire  denial  of  the  essential  unity  of 
mankind,  various  strata  or  grades  of  men  have  been  assumed, 
the  first  of  which  were  still  wholly  allied  to  the  brutes,  and 
had  no  notion  of  religion  :  thus  Schelling.^  But  this  view 
SO  destroys  the  unity  of  the  human  race,  that  even  the  unity 
of  the  moral  constitution  and  of  moral  duty  can  no  longer  be 
maintained.  Assuming  that  there  were,  or  had  been,  such 
beings  as  were  human  in  outward  appearance,  but  absolutely 
without  rational  faculties,  then  these  beings  could  not  pro- 
perly be  called  men,  and  would  therefore  here  concern  us 
no  further.  But  the  existence  of  such  tribes  has  not  as 
yet  been  demonstrated.  In  defence  of  slavery  especially  it 
has  been  attempted  to  prove  that  the  negro  is   a   different 

'  This  essential  unity  is  assumed  by  A.  v.  Humboldt. 

^  A  kindred  view  was  expressed  in  the  seventeenth  century  by  Peyreriiis  in 
his  hypothesis  of  the  pre- Adamites. 


166  §  15.    THE  EACES  AND  NATIONALITIES. 

species  of   man    derived  from   apes   or    relapsed  into  them. 
But  these  and  similar  attempts  have  all  been  failures. 

(&)  To  this  view,  which  magnifies  the  differences  of  race 
till  it  destroys  the  unity  of  mankind,  has  been  opposed,  in 
the  last  few  decades,  a  contrary  view,  at  present  very  widely 
spread.  This  later  view  not  merely  combats  the  specific 
difference  of  the  races,  but  would  trace  back  all  the  difference 
of  the  various  species  to  the  mere  variation  of  a  few  original 
types,  or  even  of  only  one.  This  is  the  hypothesis  of  Darwin, 
carried  yet  further  by  Hackel.  The  followers  of  Darwin 
refuse  to  recognise  different  acts  of  creation,  or  specifically 
different  classes  of  created  things.  Eather,  they  would  regard 
the  vegetable,  the  animal,  the  psychical,  only  as  varieties  of 
one  and  the  same  essence,  and  would  reduce  them  all  to 
mechanism.  In  the  course  of  millions  of  years,  differences 
originally  slight  are  thought  to  have  developed  themselves 
into  the  variety  of  beings  which  we  now  see.  According  to 
the  law,  that  in  the  struggle  for  existence  the  stronger 
conquers,  and  also  the  law  of  natural  selection,  of  adapta- 
tion, of  heredity,  and  the  like,  it  is  said  to  have  come  to 
pass  that  higher  and  higher  grades  of  beings  have  been 
developed,  all  of  which,  however,  have  taken  their  origin 
from  what  was  originally  the  same.  This  view  is  favoured 
by  the  more  recent  naturalists  in  increasing  numbers  ;  and 
it  recommends  itself  also  by  its  endeavour  to  see  all  the 
variety  of  tilings  in  this  world  in  their  unity  and  connection. 
For  instead  of  utterly  abandoning  the  unity  even  of  the 
human  race,  Darwinism  sees  in  the  world  one  chain  or 
ascending  series  of  beings,  of  which  the  lower — by  a  process 
immeasurably  long,  to  be  sure — are  raised  to  the  highest  which 
has  been  developed  up  to  the  present  time,  i.e.  to  the  human 
being.  But  looked  at  more  closely,  the  Darwinian  view, 
although  it  regards  with  favour  the  unity  of  man,  yet  in  that 
which  is  of  most  weight  is  at  one  with  the  first-mentioned 
view.  For  it  too  abolishes,  only  in  a  different  way  from  tlie 
former  view,  the  specific  difference  between  brutes  and  men, 
and  is  therefore  opposed  to  the  ethical  idea  of  man.  The 
ground  of  this  agreement  in  the  same  error,  in  the  case  of 
J;heories  otherwise  opposites,  lies  in  the  fact  that  both  in 
defining  the  nature  of  man  disregard  the  soul. 


THE  DARWINIAN  THEORY.  167 

(c)  Hence  both  these  views  are  opposed  by  a  multitude  of 
the  most  eminent  naturalists  and  philosophers,  as  Alexander 
von  Humboldt,  von  Bar,  Agassiz,  Braun,  the  Duke  of  Argyll, 
Wigand,  Steffens,  Schubert,  Schaller,  Planck,  Waitz,  Lotze, 
Ulrici,  Harms.  A  large  number  of  noted  naturalists  assume 
both  the  specific  difference  between  mankind  and  the  brute 
creation,  and  also  the  unity  of  the  hunian  race,  which  is 
regarded  as  forming  a  single  species,  so  that  the  so-called 
races  may  be  looked  upon  as  the  variation  of  one  and  the 
same  work  of  creation.  Blumenbach  showed  how,  in  the 
case  of  brutes  and  of  men,  the  same  laws  determine  the 
variability  of  types  ;  men,  he  says,  cannot  be  called  more 
than  one  species,  since  among  brutes  of  one  and  the  same 
species  there  can  be  shown  variations  in  respect  to  size, 
colour,  hair,  form  of  skull,  etc,  (produced  by  climate,  food, 
manner  of  life),  which  are  as  great  as  the  differences  among 
the  most  different  races  of  men,  and  even  greater  than  these. 
Waitz  has  discussed  this  question  in  detail,  in  an  especially 
thorough  and  instructive  manner,  in  opposition  to  the  first 
view.  By  examination  of  the  single  peculiarities,  even  of 
the  negro  race,  he  has  arrived  at  the  result  that  all  differences 
of  race  may  be  explained  as  variations  of  one  human  species. 
As  to  the  black  colour,  for  instance,  a  moist,  hot  climate 
with  little  shelter  from  woods  has,  he  says,  the  greatest 
influence  on  the  colour  of  hair  and  skin,  and  occasions,  in 
particular,  that  more  carbon  from  the  vegetable  food  remains 
in  the  organism,  without  becoming  burnt  up  and  consumed 
by  oxygen,  and  is  deposited  under  the  epidermis.  And 
Eudolph  Wagner  has  shown,  by  numerous  examinations, 
that  the  human  brain,  even  when  it  is  not  specially  dis- 
tinguished by  weight,  has  as  its  peculiarity  the  great  number 
of  its  convolutions.  Even  Burmeister  acknowledges  the 
specific  difference  between  the  negro  and  the  ape ;  and 
the  recently  discovered  ape,  the  gorilla,  competed  with  the 
human  species  only  for  a  short  time,  till  his  habits  were 
better  learned.  He  warms  himself,  to  be  sure,  at  the  fire 
which  the  negro  has  abandoned ;  but  he  does  not  even  know 
how  to  feed  the  fire,  and  has  fewer  convolutions  in  the  brain 
than  other  apes. 

But  against  Darwinism  it  has  been  justly  urged  that  neither 


168  §  15.    THE  RACES  AND  NATIONALITIES. 

the  struggle  for  existence  nor  heredity  explains  how  differences 
arise,  but  rather  only  how  they  maintain  themselves  and  suc- 
cessfully spread  when  they  once  exist.  The  diversity  of 
creative  thoughts  and  acts  is  denied  only  at  the  cost  of  putting 
mere  unthinking  chance  in  the  place  of  a  creative  wisdom 
that  aims  more  and  more  at  perfection ;  but  this  involves  a 
far  darker  enigma  than  faith  in  divine  activity  working  with  an 
aim.  In  Darwinism  there  also  prevails  a  very  unsatisfactory 
notion  of  unity.  The  unity  of  the  world  is  made  to  consist 
merely  in  the  likeness  of  the  matter  governed  by  mechanical 
laws.  But  what  sort  of  a  unity  would  there  be,  if  one  and 
the  same  substance  should  separate  into  an  endless  variety  of 
forms,  accidental  and  made  by  outward  influences,  without 
this  variety  itself  being  again  combined  into  a  unity  by  an 
inward  connection  ?  The  world  can  be  apprehended  as  a 
unit  only  when  it  is  conceived  of  as  a  living  organism. 
But  this  is  a  union  of  things  different.  If  we  go  back  only 
to  sameness  of  matter  and  its  mechanical  laws,  a  combination 
of  diversity  and  of  unity  in  the  world  is  not  to  be  found ; 
this  is  found  only  in  teleology,  or  tendency  to  an  end.  Braun 
has  rightly  attempted  to  find  the  union  of  these  by  assuming 
a  thought  or  type  which  nature  in  its  gradations  is  tending 
towards  (the  idea  of  man).  The  earlier  structures,  according 
to  his  view,  in  part  foreshadow  this  type,  in  part  prepare 
the  way  for  it.  It  is  the  rule  or  law  of  the  teleologically 
advancing  creation,  and  so  holds  together  in  unity  both  the 
endless  diversity  of  forms  and  the  multiplicity  of  material 
substances.  This  conception  lays  the  chief  stress  on  the  dis- 
tinguishing form  or  the  shaping  thought,  not  on  matter. 
A  similar  view  is  lield  by  Von  Biir,  who  seeks  to  prove  that 
there  is  in  nature  a  tendency  to  an  end.  But  this  is  possible 
only  on  condition  that  the  infinite  variety  of  forms  is  subject 
to  a  divine  plan,  by  which  the  variety  is  produced  and  held 
together. 

But  the  chief  argument  which  serves  to  overthrow  the  two 
opposing  theories  is  found  in  the  fact  that  man's  peculiarity 
lies  mainly  on  the  spiritual  side.  But  this  Darwinism  does  not 
explain  ;  it  does  not  take  into  accoimt  that  by  the  difference 
m  mental  traits  animals  and  human  beings  are  held  apart  as 
two  specifically  different  genera.      The  spirit  in  man  is  explic- 


UNITY  OF  THE  HUMAN  SPECIES.  169 

aljle  only  as  being  a  new  impartation  made  by  God  to  the 
animated  dust,  after  the  time  had  come  for  the  appearance  of 
man.  Man  in  relation  to  nature  is  supernatural,  a  miracle, 
referable  to  God's  creative  omnipotence  alone.  There  is  there- 
fore no  reason  for  departing  from  the  Bible,  which,  with  refer- 
ence to  the  nianifoldness  of  creatures,  includes,  according  to 
Gen.  i.,  the  notion  of  species  in  the  original  thought  of  creation 
and  in  its  realization/  Likewise  it  is  possible  successfully 
to  maintain  the  essential  intrinsic  unity  of  mankind,  so 
long  as  for  human  beings  the  chief  stress  is  laid  upon  the 
psychical  nature  and  the  rational  constitution.  The  essential 
faculties  of  the  soul,  which  are  found  in  all  men,  make 
possible  a  common  culture  and  a  gradual  overcoming  of  even 
profound  differences  which  have  arisen  through  abnormalness. 
The  descent  of  all  mankind  from  one  original  pair  would 
indeed  prove  most  cogently  the  unity  of  the  human  race. 
This  unity  cannot,  however,  be  decisively  proved  by  a  natural 
science  that  is  conscious  of  its  own  limitations ;  but  it  is  only 
recommended,  first,  by  the  Biblical  records  of  the  Old  and 
Xew  Testaments,  and  next  by  historical  indications,  as  com- 
mon traditions,  legends,  affinities  of  languages ;  finally,  the 
gaps  in  the  evidence  which,  after  all  this,  still  remain  can  be 
supplemented  by  the  considerations  which  it  is  the  province 
of  dogmatics  to  urge.^ 

3.  Having  limited  the  significance  of  the  race-distinctions 
so  far  as  is  necessary  for  ethics,  let  us  glance  further  at  the 
nature  of  them  in  their  connection  with  the  unity  of  man. 
The  differences  of  race  may  perhaps  be  brought  into  connec- 
tion with  the  doctrine  of  the  temi^eraments ;  and  it  may  be 
assumed  that  the  four  permanent  fundamental  moods  which 
are  possible  in  human  nature,  and  which  may  manifest  them- 
selves, not  only  in  individuals,  but  also  among  large  masses 
of  men  (§  14&),  furnish  the  principal  ground  of  explanation 
for  everything  essential  in  the  differences  of  race  and  of 
nationality.  This  view  commends  itself  especially  when  we 
recall  the  above-mentioned  physical  basis  of  the  temperaments  ; 
for,  1.  In  the  phlegmatic  temperament  there  is  found  a  lym- 

'"  Gen.  i.  11,  12,  22.     He  created  each  thing  according  to  its  kind,  so  that  it 
has  its  seed  in  itself,  in  order  to  propagate  its  nature. 
^  See  Corner's  System  of  C'hristicia  Doctrine,  i.  §  43. 


170  §  15.    THE  EACES  AND  NATIONALITIES. 

phatic  constitution,  a  predominance  of  vegetative  life,  of  the 
cellular  and  glandular  system.  But  the  same  is  found  also 
in  the  Ethiopian  race.  2.  The  arterial  constitution  is  the 
choleric  ;  it  is  found  especially  in  the  Caucasian  race.  3.  The 
venous  constitution,  or  the  predominance  of  the  venous  and 
ganglionic  systems,  prevails  in  the  melancholic  temperament, 
and  is  met  with  in  the  Mongolian  race.  4.  The  nervous  or 
sangvinc  constitution  has  perhaps  in  the  Polynesians  the  most 
striking  representatives.  The  actual  origin  of  the  races  may 
then  be  conceived  of  in  the  following  way :  The  four  possible 
types  of  habitual  fundamental  mood  into  which  the  life  of 
individuals  can  pass,  are  germinally  involved  in  human  nature 
itself.  What  the  fundamental  mood  or  temperament  of  the 
descendants  shall  be  is  especially  dependent  upon  the  consti- 
tution and  mood  of  the  parents  at  the  time  when  they  become 
parents.  As,  now,  this  fundamental  mood  may  have  been 
more  and  more  widely  transmitted,  so  these  differences,  if  the 
descendants  of  like  kind  sought  and  found  an  outward  nature 
in  affinity  with  them,  may,  in  the  course  of  hundreds  and 
thousands  of  years,  by  geographical  and  climatic  conditions,  by 
men's  associating  predominantly  with  those  of  tlieir  own  sort, 
and  finally,  by  the  operation  of  abnormal  influences,  have  been 
developed  and  confirmed  to  the  degree  which  the  most  marked 
races  now  existing  present.  Thus  viewed,  the  races  would 
be,  as  it  were,  temperaments  or  fundamental  moods  of  human 
nature,  fixed,  though  manifesting  themselves  in  most  manifold 
degrees,  and  to  some  extent  in  combinations. 

In  agreement  with  this  are  both  the  organic  differences  of 
the  races  and  also  their  psychical  peculiarities.  There  is  the 
most  unanimity  in  regarding  the  Caucasian  and  the  negro 
races  as  separate  races ;  psychically,  too,  they  correspond 
most  clearly  to  the  choleric  and  phlegmatic  temperaments,  and 
they  stand  on  the  globe  opposite  to  each  other,  like  north 
and  south.  To  the  Caucasian  race  belong  most  of  the 
peoples  of  Europe,  the  whole  Indo-Germanic  race,  i.e.  the 
(ireeks,  Eomans,  Germans,  Celts,  Slavs,  also  the  Persians,  the 
inhabitants  of  Western  India,  and  the  Egyptians.  To  the 
Ethiopian  or  negro  race  belong  most  of  the  peoples  and  tribes  of 
Africa ;  their  territory  extended  formerly,  being  called  that  of 
the  Cushites,  far  into  southern  Asia,  until  tlie  Aryans  crowded 


RACES  AS  RELATED  TO  TEMPERAMENTS.  l7l 

in.  Among  the  other  races  the  Mongolian  is  distinguished  by 
marked  characteristics ;  to  it  belong  Eastern  India,  China, 
Japan,  the  Mongols,  Huns,  Kalmucks,  Lapps,  Finns,  and 
Esquimaux,  and  also  a  part  at  least  of  the  original  population 
of  America.  They  correspond,  not  only  physically,  as  to  their 
straight  black  hair  and  dark-yellow  or  brown  skin,  but  also 
psychically,  as  to  their  depressed  and  gloomy  nature,  most 
nearly  to  the  melancholic  temperament.  The  least  numerous,  so 
far  as  can  be  known,  are  the  representatives  of  the  sanguine 
temperament,  with  their  lively  excitability  and  volatile  enjoy- 
ment of  life.  We  have,  however,  no  right  to  assume  that  these 
differences  developed  themselves  or  became  fixed  in  the  very 
first  generations  of  mankind ;  for  human  nature  has  still, 
everywhere  and  always,  more  or  less  the  ability,  even  if  it  be 
only  for  the  time  being,  to  pass  over  into  the  different  funda- 
mental moods,  and  to  be  productive  in  them.  In  every 
nation  are  the  various  temperaments,  and  likewise  such 
tendencies  towards  the  various  races  as  under  favouring  cir- 
cumstances may  develope  themselves ;  and  with  this  may  be 
connected  the  fact,  that  even  now,  e.g.,  in  European  families, 
tliere  sometimes  suddenly  appear  individuals  who  possess  a 
number  of  the  peculiarities  of  a  foreign  race,  and  who  thus 
probably  have  also  a  psychical  tendency  in  the  same  direction. 
Furthermore,  the  differences  of  race  must  not  be  viewed  as 
differences  which  are  in  themselves  to  continue  for  ever  in 
their  absolute  one-sidedness.  It  is  rather  a  part  of  the  moral 
mission  of  the  human  species  that  the  races  and  nations 
should  appropriate  one  another's  excellences,  as  far  as  the 
perfecting  of  their  own  individuality  allows  it  or  requires  it. 
It  is  an  end  in  the  history  of  the  world  that  the  nations 
should  not  be  left  to  their  natura,  which  may  in  itself  be 
very  poor  and  imperfect,  but  that  by  combinations  which,  as 
is  well  known,  may  take  place  with  fruitful  results  among  all 
races,  they  should  exhibit  more  varied  and  more  permanent 
national  peculiarities,  in  which  there  is  no  danger  of  uni- 
formity, but  rather  a  tendency  to  so  much  the  richer  diversity. 
Thus  almost  all  the  nations  which  stand  highest  in  the  world 
came  to  their  national  character,  as  it  now  is,  through  the 
different  strata  of  nations  gradually  depositing  themselves  one 
upon  another,  and  undergoing  a  process  of  physical  and  mental 


172  §  15.    THE  EACES  AND  NATIONALITIES. 

assimilation.  This  process  produced  a  mutual  improvement, 
and  called  forth  a  nationality  which  did  not  originally  exist 
of  itself,  but  was  the  result  only  of  history  and  of  the 
influence  of  spiritual  forces.  If  the  historical  spiritual  factor  is 
disregarded,  one  may  come,  in  his  enthusiasm  for  nationalities, 
to  a  sort  of  naturalism  that  undervalues  the  spiritual  side 
of  man,  which  has  a  tendency  towards  universal  exchange, 
although  nature  must  be  guarded  as  the  basis  and  starting- 
point  for  the  universal  receptiveness.  The  English  nationality, 
e.g.,  to  which  no  one  ascribes  deficiency  in  sharply-defined 
traits,  has  become  historically  what  it  is  by  the  commingling 
of  the  old  -  British,  Gaelic,  Eoman  (Latin)  type  with 
Anglo-Saxon,  Danish,  and  Norman  elements.  The  case  is 
similar  with  the  German,  the  French,  and  Spanish  nation- 
alities, as  the  consequence  of  many  hundred  years  of  continued 
migrations ;  the  case  was  similar  even  with  the  Greeks  and  the 
Romans.  Perhaps,  too,  there  remain  in  the  present  nations 
race-distinctions  which  have  already  been  in  some  measure 
overcome  by  historical  agencies.  Thus  the  Gaels,  Basques, 
and  Irish  are  perhaps  remnants  of  a  preponderantly  sanguine 
race ;  the  Mongolian  race,  likewise,  shows  in  the  Hungarians 
and  Turks  an  improvement  upon  the  original  type.  The 
negro  seems,  indeed,  to  be  more  stereotyped  on  account  of 
his  dulness ;  but  it  is  not  till  recently  that  he  has  begun  to 
come  again  into  the  general  intercourse  of  nations  ;  formerly 
also  he  occupied  a  higher  position,  at  least  in  some  respects. 
Even  before  the  Caucasian  race  came  upon  the  stage  of  the 
world's  history,  negro  kingdoms  were  formed  as  far  as  into 
Asia;  and  even  at  the  present  time  there  are  (according  to 
Earth,  Livingstone,  Vogel,  and  others)  large,  well-ordered, 
agricultural  negro  states  in  Central  Africa.  It  is  especially 
the  European  slave-trade  which  has  so  degraded  him  on  the 
sea-coasts,  and  even  there,  where  it  is  most  degraded,  the 
negro  race  shows  plasticity,  susceptibility  for  culture  and  for 
Christianity ;  and  by  both  these,  as  well  as  by  amalgamation, 
it  will  be  able  to  attain  a  higher  grade  of  existence. 

4.  The  difference  of  races  has  doubtless  not  come  to  its 
present  extreme  without  the  influence  of  sin,  and  would  be, 
under  normal  development,  more  nearly  the  same  macro- 
cosmically  that  brothers  and  sisters  in  the  family  circle  are 


THE  TKUE  IMPORTANCE  OF  NATIONAL  DISTINCTIONS.       173 

microcosmically.  And  a  similar  analogy  again  may  be  found 
in  the  nations  of  the  same  race  as  they  are  related  to  one 
another.  On  account  of  this  abnormal  influence  of  sin,  it 
cannot  belong  to  us  to  deduce  ft  ^j)7'io?"i  what  the  variety  of 
races  and  nations  may  become.  It  may  also  be  doubted 
whether  the  nations,  as  collections  of  masses  of  individuals  of 
a  more  homogeneous  sort,  are  destined  to  permanent  con- 
tinuance. And  altliough,  for  the  course  of  history,  the 
existence  of  mankind  in  distinct  nations  is  warranted ;  and 
further,  although  the  national  spirit  has  also  a  determining 
and  enriching  influence  on  every  individual  singly,  and  on 
the  development  of  that  germ  in  him  which  is  eternal ;  yet 
the  right  and  the  value  of  nationality  ought  not  to  be  over- 
estimated. Else  there  would  be  danger  of  a  naturalism  which 
might  be  disposed  to  assert  itself  in  opposition  to  the  ethical 
work  which  it  is  the  part  of  history  to  accomplish,  and  in 
exclusiveness  or  even  enmity  towards  other  nations,  and  also 
in  opposition  to  the  ends  which  the  universal  fellowship  of 
the  Church  and  of  the  kingdom  of  God  must  aim  at. 
Christianity  proclaims.  There  is  neither  Greek  nor  Jew, 
neither  barbarian  nor  Scythian,  but  all  are  one  in  Christ ; 
hence  Christian  ethics,  especially  in  our  day,  must  admonish 
against  an  exaggeration  of  the  value  of  nationality,  and  of  a 
patriotism  founded  upon  it.  In  the  state  of  perfection,  the 
distribution  of  individuals  will  not  be,  as  now,  according  to 
the  principle  of  nationality,  but  according  to  the  principle 
of  spirituality.  Tongues  shall  cease  ;  and  everlasting  con- 
tinuance is  as  little  promised  to  the  German  or  to  the 
English  nation,  as  to  the  Turks  or  the  Russians.  But  yet 
for  the  moulding  of  the  life  and  essential  nature  of  man  on 
the  earth,  there  must  be  assumed  (1)  a  collocation  of  peoples 
and  of  countries  according  to  their  vocation  in  the  world's 
history  (Acts  xvii.  26);  (2)  a  necessity,  at  least  for  a  time, 
that  such  great  homogeneous  masses  abide  together,  since  it  is 
only  as  a  peculiarity  takes  on  a  distinct  form  among  great 
masses  that  each  main  peculiarity  can  really  become  strong, 
and  can  exhibit  its  nature  in  life ;  (3)  the  significance  of 
national  distinctions  even  for  the  individual  peculiarities  which 
are  destined  to  immortality. 


174  §  IG.    THE  TALENTS. 


§  IG.   The  Talents. 

The  second  main  class  of  the  sources  of  individuality,  that, 
namely,  which  relates  to  activity,  affords  a  variety,  large 
indeed,  but  yet  limited ;  for  there  are  definite  talents 
for  particular  individual  moral  spheres,  and  they  thus 
constitute  the  subjective  foundation  for  the  individual 
vocation,  which  is  ethically  determined  by  one's  talents. 
The  family  and  the  Church  are  general,  and  not  par- 
ticular, moral  spheres ;  whereas  the  other  moral  depart- 
ments belonging  to  the  earthly  manifestation  of  a  moral 
universe  furnish  also  the  basis  for  classifying  the  chief 
varieties  of  talents.  An  especial  affinity  may  indeed 
exist  between  certain  constitutional  temperaments  and 
certain  talents ;  but  the  talents  are  directed  towards 
self-activity,  it  being  only  by  exercise  and  activity  that 
they  acquire  force.  But  that  they  are  connected  with 
the  constitutional  condition  is  shown  by  their  being 
hereditary,  as  is  perceived  in  the  case,  at  least,  of  such 
talents  as  are  more  closely  connected  with  nature. 

])[ote. — Heredity  is  manifest,  e.g.,  especially  in  reference  to  the 
talent  for  the  comparatively  low  departments  of  music  and 
mathematics ;  but  less  in  reference  to  a  gift  for  statesmanship 
or  for  science. 

1.  What  nature  has  denied  to  one  nation,  while  it  has 
furnished  it  to  another,  seems  to  be  incapable  of  being 
in  any  way  retrieved  by  the  first,  but  to  involve  for 
it  a  permanent  inferiority  in  comparison  with  others.  But 
this  is  not  the  case.  The  products  of  eminent  talents  can  be 
for  the  good  of  all ;  and  even  for  that  for  which  one  has  no 
productiveness  he  has  yet  the  susceptibility.  The  moral 
process,  while  it  also  developes  susceptibility,  often,  when 
this  has  been  satisfied,  has  the  effect  of  eliciting  productive- 
ness, although  the  productiveness  is  modified  in  its  individual 
forms  by  the  variety  in  the  starting-point  of  the  development. 
And  though  indeed,  at  any  given  time,  different  nations  are 


TALENTS  AKE  TO  BE  ETHICALLY  USED.  175 

distinguished  for  different  talents,  e.g.  in  ancient  times  the 
Eoman,  in  modern  times  the  English,  for  statesmanship ;  the 
Greeks  formerly,  the  Germans  in  modern  times,  for  science  ; 
yet,  too,  one  and  the  same  nation  at  different  periods  of  its 
history  can  by  virtue  of  special  talents  do  successful  work  in 
different  departments.  Thus  the  Italians,  the  successors  of 
the  unartistic  Eomans,  have  cultivated  art ;  and  thus  in  recent 
times  the  Germans,  together  with  the  culture  of  art  and  science, 
have  made  advance  in  statesmanship  also. 

2.  The  absolute  worth  of  the  personality  is  dependent  upon 
its  moral  worth,  and  not  upon  talent,  which  is  primarily  a 
natural  gift;  but  talent  does  decide  what  is  the  correct 
manifestation  of  the  moral  personality.  Furthermore,  talents 
have  an  abiding  significance,  when  they  are  made  eternal  by 
means  of  moral  consecration ;  and  this  holds  true  not  merely 
of  the  talents  which  lie  immediately  within  the  realm  of 
mind ;  other  talents  also  can  express  a  definite  mental 
character,  as  it  manifests  itself  in  apprehension,  in  production, 
and  in  mode  of  execution.  But  all  natural  gifts,  in  order  to  the 
full  realization  of  the  creative  thought,  may  be  laid  hold  of  by 
the  Divine  Spirit  and  be  consecrated  as  charismata ;  as  even 
in  the  Old  Testament  the  plastic  and  poetic  arts,  as  well  as 
wisdom,  are  traced  back  to  the  Spirit  of  God ;  yes,  it  is  in 
accordance  with  the  Bible  when  we  conceive  of  charismata, 
like  those  of  a  Paul,  or  of  an  Augustine,  not  merely  as  limited 
to  the  earthly  life,  but  as  shining  eternally  in  unfading 
splendour.^ 

3.  What  has  been  said  stands  opposed  to  the  falsely 
democratic,  and  to  the  falsely  aristocratic,  conception  of 
talents.  According  to  the  former,  the  justice  of  God  demands 
that  all  individuals  in  themselves  be  naturally  alike,  and  each 
be  able  to  become  what  the  others  can  become ;  it  holds  that 
great  men  have  become  great  only  through  their  opportunity ; 
that  the  differences  have  been  brought  about  only  tlirough 
outward  circumstances,  culture,  and  training.  Connected 
with  this  also  is  the  false  principle,  that  whatever  a  person 
may  contribute  that  is  new  is  to  be  explained  from  his  sur- 
roundings. But  in  that  case  the  constitution  of  the  universe, 
as  divinely  planned,  would  be  very  uniform,  and  the  question 

^  Dan.  xii.  3  ;  Matt.  xxv.  15  sq. 


176  §  IC.   THE  TALENTS,       FALSE  CONCEPTIONS. 

as  to  the  origin  of  the  differences  would  only  be  postponed. 
We  cannot  see,  either,  how  an  inequality  originally  ordained 
should  be  more  unjust  than  one  produced  by  outward  circum- 
stances. It  betrays  a  want  of  culture  to  have  no  appreciation 
of  the  moving  of  an  original  spirit  in  such  creative  natures 
as  have  revolutionized  their  times  by  somehow  adding  to 
that  which  was  already  existent  the  power  of  a  higher  unifying 
principle. 

On  the  other  side,  no  less  false  is  an  aristocratic  conception 
of  talent,  which  is  inclined  to  assume  that  geniuses  are 
emancipated  from  the  ordinary  moral  law,  and  to  make  them 
the  objects  of  a  sort  of  worship,  as  if  they  were  superior 
beings.  A  certain  equalization  of  the  diff"erences  between 
favoured  minds  and  the  masses  lies  in  the  very  fact  that  the 
superior  gifts  of  the  former  exist  for  the  masses,  who  are  by 
this  means  to  be  elevated.  All  rule  in  the  realm  of  mind  is 
service ;  all  have  need  of  all,  and  are  conditioned  by  one 
another ;  no  one  can  say,  I  have  no  need  of  thee.^  All  have 
talents,  and  these  differences  will  last.  During  the  period  of 
development  it  may  happen,  now,  that  one  person  feels  him- 
self to  be  poor  and  empty  in  comparison  with  others,  and 
would  rather  have  a  different  individuality,  or  would  like  to 
■exchange  it  for  another.  But  then  he  does  not  know  either 
what  his  own,  or  what  the  other,  individuality  is ;  indeed,  he 
is  in  bald  contradiction  with  himself;  for  on  the  one  hand  he 
would  like  to  continue  to  be,  and  has  a  wish  for  this  continued 
being,  and  on  the  other  hand  he  wishes  to  be  that  which 
would  involve  his  own  non  -  existence.  There  is  in  each 
individuality  a  sacred,  eternal  germ,  which  should  be  guarded 
and  developed,  but  can  be  neglected  and  dwarfed.  Hence  it 
is  both  abnormal  and  wicked,  not  to  be  willing  to  be  that 
which  is  the  divine  thought  of  one's  own  self.  The  passion 
for  imitation  does  a  work  of  destruction,  let  another's  indi- 
viduality stand  ever  so  high.  Absolutely  universal  is  only  one 
— Christ ;  in  all  other  persons  we  may  indeed  imitate  that  which 
is  common,  but  not  that  which  is  individual,  as,  e.g.,  in  a  Paul 
or  a  Luther.  The  opposite  fault  is  that  of  shutting  one's  self 
up  in  one's  own  individuality,  in  a  separatistic  way,  or  of 
affecting  singularity  in  straining  to  be  original. 

'  Matt.  XX.  2G  ;  1  Cor.  xii.  21  sq.  ;  Matt.  xxv.  21  ;  Lwke  xix.  24. 


§  17.    UNIFYING  TENDENCIES  IN  HUMAN  NATUKE.  177 

Note  1. — However  great  may  be  the  variety  of  individuali- 
ties resulting  from  the  above  treated  sources  of  individuation 
(§  13-16), — peculiarities  which  are  permanent,  too,  by  reason  of 
the  different  starting-points  and  of  the  order  of  the  factors  which 
enter  into  the  structure  of  the  personal  character, — yet  this 
multitude  is  not  one  that  continues  to  expand  itself  indefinitely. 
As  our  race  had  a  beginning,  so  its  procreations  will  also  have 
an  end,  when  the  full  number  is  attained  which  belongs  to  the 
notion  of  complete  humanity.  But  this  full  number  is  a 
definite  one,  otherwise  a  teleological  place  for  it  would  be 
excluded.  Only  thus,  too,  can  each  person  have  his  definite 
place  within  the  sphere  of  humanity. 

Note  2. — We  have  considered  that  which  is  common  in  the 
moral  endowment,  and  then  that  which  is  individual,  into 
which  the  common  branches  out.  Now,  however,  in  a  third 
section  we  have  to  see  how  even  in  the  natural  constitution  are 
also  contained  principles  through  which  these  diversities  and 
divisions  are  brought  back  into  a  unity,  although  not  at  once  a 
perfect  unity. 


THIRD   SECTION". 

THE  IMMEDIATE  OR  NATUEAL  UNION  OF  THE  DIFFERENCES  IN 
HUMAN  NATURE. 

§17. 

The  diversity  of  the  moral  faculties,  thus  far  considered,  and 
the  differentiating  of  human  nature,  is  happily  balanced 
by  a  natural  tendency  of  these  faculties  and  differences 
to  come  together,  both  in  individuals  and  in  the  race, — 
by  an  inborn  unifying  force,  which  is  effectual  to  form  a 
natural  counterpoise  against  disunion  and  confusion. 
But  this  natural  union  can  have  been  implanted  only  as 
a  provisional  one,  and  does  not  exempt  from  the  duty  of 
uniting  the  faculties  ethically.  This  natural  union,  being 
at  first  merely  a  loose  one,  awaits  the  free  moral  action 
which  comes  after  moral  duty  and  moral  good  are  recog- 
nised. Just  on  this  account  it  is  also  exposed  to  dissolu- 
tion and  confusion  through  arbitrary  choice.  Nevertheless 
by  this  natural  action  of  the  innate  unifying  power,  by 
M 


178  §  17.    UNIFYING  TENDENCIES  IN  HUMAN  NATURE. 

means  of  the  forces  that  it  sets  in  motion,  there  is  pro- 
duced a  prototype  or  outline  of  the  future  ethical 
shaping  of  the  world — a  prototype  which  constitutes  the 
starting-point  and  actual  foundation  for  the  conscious 
ethical  process. 

Note,. — The  thesis  aims  to  set  forth  (1)  how  in  man,  as 
naturally  constituted,  notwithstanding  the  variety  in  each  one's 
faculties,  and  notwithstanding  the  differences  of  different  indi- 
viduals, yet  the  unity  also  makes  itself  felt,  and  how  this,  as  a 
natural  unity,  exhibits  another  important  and  efficient  element 
in  man's  ethical  endowment.  But  next  (2)  it  is  to  be  shown  that 
this  natural  unity  is  only  an  antecedent  condition  of  morality, 
but  is  neither  moral  in  itself  nor  productive  of  morality, 
because,  and  so  long  as,  that  which  is  addressed  to  the  will, 
viz.  absolute  and  unconditional  worth,  has  presented  itself 
neither  in  the  consciousness  nor  in  the  will.  How  early  the 
ethical  factor  itself  makes  its  appearance  is  not  here  affirmed ; 
for  the  present  purpose  it  is  important  only  to  see  what  the 
natural  equipment  can  accomplish  in  and  of  itself,  even  though 
not  from  ethical  motives.  For  by  tliis  means  it  becomes  plain 
what  can  be  done  simply  and  alone  by  the  moral  principle.  It 
is  accordingly  not  meant  by  this  to  deny  that  the  moral  element 
makes  an  entrance,  at  least  sporadically,  even  though  not 
at  once  dominantly,  into  the  beginnings  of  humanity.  But 
evidently  there  are  many  living  who  are  not  clearly  determined 
by  the  idea'  of  morality,  since  they  get  no  farther  than  the 
stage  of  natural  eudaemony,  as,  with  Chalybaus,  we  may  briefly 
designate  it. 

1.  The  natural  hcginnijigs  of  human  civilisation  resulting 
from  the  principle  of  self-;preservation.  All  the  endowments 
of  man,  both  common  and  individual,  are  directly  unified  or 
united  in  man's  natural  personality.  The  person,  as  a  natural 
unity,  has  them  all,  although  they  wait  to  receive  their  moral 
stamp  first  from  the  act  of  the  free  person.  This  unity,  the 
natural  person,  is  normally  active  even  without  the  free  act  of 
the  will  conscious  of  moral  duty.  For  it  is  created  as  a  living 
personality,  consequently  one  that  preserves  itself,  as  respects 
both  what  is  physical  and  what  is  mental,  both  what  is  common 
and  what  is  individual.  There  takes  place  a  natural  co- 
operation and  interpenetration  not  merely  of  the  faculties  of 
the  bodily  organism,  but  also  of  those  of  the  mental  being 
(§  10.  2,  §  11,  §  12.  1,  2).      There  is  also  a  natural  tendency 


SELF-PEE3ERVATI0X  AND  DOMINION  OVER  NATUEE,        179 

and  endeavour  after  union  among  the  differences  of  the  different 
individuals,  so  that  human  nature,  after  having  developed  into 
variety,  seeks  out  of  tliis  variety  again  to  restore  itself  to 
unity,  and  does  so  in  a  measure.  By  force  of  natural  impulse 
human  nature  manifests  itself  as  a  unity,  but  so  that  every- 
thing aims  at  sclf-;prcservation  only,  not  as  yet  at  history  and 
moral  development ;  for  to  this  end  a  conscious  ethical  goal 
would  be  necessary.  But  mere  self-preservation  makes  a  large 
circle  of  activities  necessary,  and  even  brings  with  it  a  certain 
culture.  These  rudiments  of  culture  produced,  as  it  were, 
spontaneously,  let  us  consider,  then,  with  reference  to  man 
himself  as  he  is  related  to  nature  and  to  social  life.^ 

The  self-preservation  of  the  natural  'personality  requires 
food,  clothing,  and  shelter,  especially  on  account  of  man's 
helplessness  at  the  beginning  of  his  existence ;  the  food  must 
be  sought,  prepared,  and  preserved.  This,  as  well  as  clothing 
and  shelter  for  protection  from  the  elements,  requires  reflection 
and  the  exercise  of  his  inborn  faculties.  But  the  psychical 
faculties  of  man  also  demand  nourishment  on  their  part,  for 
instance,  cognition,  or  the  satisfaction  of  the  love  of  know- 
ledge. The  circle  of  this  desire  enlarges  more  and  more,  and 
by  means  of  it  the  soul  is  filled  with  knowledge  of  nature 
both  outward  and  inward,  and  of  the  laws  according  to  which 
it  needs  to  be  treated. 

2.  Nature  (outward  nature)  was  given  to  man  for  him  to 
have  dommion  over  (Gen.  i.  28) ;  nor  was  this  gift  revoked 
after  the  fall  (ix.  2  sq. ;  Ps.  viii.)  ;  he  has  also  impulses  and 
faculties  answering  thereto.  Man  naturally,  by  a  necessity 
of  his  being,  from  need  and  impulse,  appropriates  nature, 
nay,  even  to  some  degree  moulds  it.  Man  takes  possession 
of  nature  (Gen.  ix.  2,  3,  iv.  22)  ;  and  that  is  the  beginning  of 
property,  that  is,  of  that  sort  of  possession  on  which  the 
stamp  of  the  natural  personality  is  imprinted.  Man  uses 
nature,  as  he  finds  it,  for  his  own  ends,  whether  it  be  by 
appropriating  the  land  to  himself  only  temporarily,  as  the 
nomad  (Gen.  iv.  20)  and  the  hunter  (Gen,  x.  9)  do,  or  per- 
manently, as  in  agriculture  and  cattle-raising  (Gen.  iv.  2). 
The    latter    lead    nearer    to    civilisation,   for    by  them    the 

'  Cf.  the  origin  of  human  society  in  the  Book  of  Genesis,  in  Plato's  Republic 
II.,  and  in  Aristotle's  Politics  I.  (tow  ?>)»  I'vsxa.) 


180  §  17.    UNIFYING  TENDENCIES  IN  HUMAN  NATUKE. 

nature  which  is  taken  possession  of  is  also  actually  culti- 
vated. The  instability  and  irregularity  of  nomadic  life 
become  exchanged  for  the  settled  life  of  agriculture  ;  and 
this  reacts  on  the  habitation,  clothing,  and  sustenance.  The 
fixed  order  and  regularity  that  characterize  climatic  relations 
and  change  of  seasons  become  a  natural  discipline,  which 
accustoms  man  to  forethought,  order,  and  frugality ;  harvest 
comes  only  after  seed-time  and  care  of  the  crops. 

Quiet  rural  life  and  its  leisure  next  give  rise  to  inven- 
tions subservient  to  man's  necessities  and  well-being  (Gen. 
iv.  22) — a  beginning  of  manufactures,  by  means  of  which 
new  portions  of  nature  are  one  after  another  drawn  into  the 
realm  of  human  industry.  The  heaped-up  stores,  however, 
require  protection  from  violence  and  artifice,  and  there 
arise  enclosed  cities  with  acropoles  (Gen.  iv.  17),  strong- 
holds, and  burghers  as  distinguished  from  countrymen. 
Naturally  there  is  produced  in  the  cities  a  particularly  high 
type  of  culture  and  of  industries,  the  branches  of  which 
support  one  another.  While  the  nomads  gradually  disappear, 
side  by  side  with  the  peasants  appear  the  citizens  with  their 
trades,  which  not  only  make  demands  on  the  hand  and  its 
dexterity,  as  in  the  case  of  the  handicrafts,  but  also  on  the 
mental  faculties,  e.g.  on  the  understanding,  which  seeks  or 
invents  what  is  fit  and  useful ;  also  on  the  taste  for  art,  and 
on  the  fancy,  which  seeks  to  make  the  world  comfortable, 
harmonious,  and  beautiful,  —  in  short,  to  make  life  happy. 
So  too  with  reference  to  architecture,  horticulture,  and  the 
strictly  plastic  arts.  In  all  these  relations  the  unity  of  the 
natural  personality  actively  asserts  itself.  It  unites  the 
faculties  for  its  own  ends,  which  although  only  finite  are  yet 
normal,  being  suggested  by  innate  impulses.  In  these  ends 
the  actual  frametvorh  for  a  moral  world  is  built  up, — the 
framework,  not  the  realization  of  the  highest  end.  The 
Cainite  line,  according  to  the  Bible,  made  this  sphere  of 
happiness  —  this  development  of  the  worldly  sense  —  the 
highest  aun  of  their  efforts  (Gen.  iv.  17,  22). 

3.  Added  to  this  are,  thirdly,  the  beginnings  of  a  social 
life  prearranged  in  nature,  a  relation  of  men  to  men.  The 
numberless  differences  which  cause  the  human  race  to  branch 
out  into  a  multiplicity  find,  irrespective  of  the  religious  and 


RELATIONS  OF  MEN  TO  MEN.  181 

moral  factor,  a  natural  counterpoise  in  the  race  feeling, 
which,  as  much  as  these  differences,  belongs  to  the  nature 
of  each  individual,  and  by  virtue  of  which  the  race  remains 
an  undivided  power.  By  the  operation  of  this  factor  it  comes 
to  pass  that  just  through  the  more  strongly  prominent  differ- 
ences there  is  produced  an  incitement  to  form  companionship, 
or  rather,  a  multitude  of  companionships.  The  variety  of  the 
differences  is  just  the  mediating  principle  by  which  particular 
classes  of  companionship  are  founded. 

(a)  Sexiud  love,  the  analogue  of  marriage. — The  two  sexes, 
the  more  independently  they  diverge  from  each  other,  strive  so 
much  the  more  for  reunion  both  physical  and  psychical ;  the 
productive  sex  needs  to  be  met  by  a  receptive  one ;  the  two 
enter  into  a  relation  of  reciprocity  and  mutual  benefaction. 
Strength  craves  grace ;  tenderness  craves  firmness  ;  when 
these  are  met  together  there  is  natural  love,  not  merely  physi- 
cal but  psychical.  Where  this  takes  a  normal  course,  there 
is  introduced  a  community  of  work  and  a  psychical  inter- 
cliange,  which  at  once  adds  more  permanence  and  stability 
to  the  relation,  by  the  mere  operation  of  a  healthy  nature. 
In  this  conjugal  association  of  the  sexes  there  is  a  prelude 
or  analogue  of  ethical  wedlock ;  the  fellowship  grows  in  inti- 
macy through  the  products  added  to  the  race.  Even  the 
higher  brutes  show  a  ray  of  mutual  piety  in  the  relation 
between  the  old  and  their  young  ;  this  is  still  more  decidedly 
the  case  with  human  parents.  The  care  which  natural  parental 
love  takes  for  the  children,  who  are  their  extended  ego, — 
their  common,  dearest  possession, — cements  the  companionship 
of  the  consorts.  Just  as  naturally  the  love  of  the  child  turns 
back  to  the  parents ;  the  child  has  a  natural  drawing  towards 
those  from  whom  it  proceeded. 

(b)  Relationship  of  hlood  and  lineage  as  analogues  of  the 
ethical  family  spirit. — The  common  origin  of  a  race  of  descen- 
dants, however  different  they  may  be,  operates  again  as  a 
bond  which  unites  the  differences.  Blood-relationship  is 
sacred  among  all  nations  by  virtue  of  a  natural  propensity  ; 
this  continues  to  operate  also  when  the  family  becomes 
enlarged  into  tribes  and  nations.  What  blood-relationship 
thus  loses  in  intensity  by  expansion,  is  made  up  by  com- 
munity of  customs,  language,  and  traditions  ;  and  when  the 


182  §  17.    UNIFYING  TENDENCIES  IN  HUMAN  NATUEE. 

connection  seems  to  have  become  loosened,  it  yet  shows 
itself  immediately  operative  iu  the  contact  with  other  tribes 
or  nationalities.  To  be  sure,  this  mere  love  of  tribe  has  in  it 
something  narrow,  or  even  selfish ;  for  the  elective  affinity 
which  produces  a  closer  union  within  the  tribe  operates  as  a 
divisive  force  in  relation  to  other  tribes  or  peoples. 

(c)  The  customs  and  habits  of  the  tribal  community  form  at 
the  same  time  a  prototype  of  the  State.  The  endeavour  of  a 
tribe  to  assert  itself  as  a  unit  against  others  calls  forth  the 
need  of  organization,  which  at  the  outset  is  borrowed  from  the 
family  type.  At  first,  the  father  is  the  head  of  the  family  ; 
later,  the  first-born  son  ;  until,  even  though  by  means  of  a 
one-sidedly  aristocratic,  democratic,  or  monarchical  constitu- 
tion, as  the  case  may  be,  the  people  are  divided  into  rulers 
and  subjects.  However  widely  different  the  regulations  of 
tribes  may  be  from  those  of  a  State,  we  yet  see  in  them 
already  something  higher  than  a  republic  of  ants  or  bees. 

(d)  Comradeship,  the  analogue  of  friendship. — ^The  difference 
of  temperaments  is  of  great  imj)ortance  in  the  domain  of  free 
social  intercourse.  At  first  this  intercourse  may  be  of  a  rather 
accidental,  atomistic  character,  and  for  mere  amusement 
(comradeship)  ;  but  it  also  assumes  stability  the  more  it  is 
connected  with  activity,  and  the  more  it  has  regard  not 
merely  to  enjoyment,  but  also  works  in  connection  with  the 
tendency  next  treated  of. 

(c)  Division  of  labour,  difference  of  talents,  and  associations 
resulting  from  identity  in  respect  to  them, — the  analogue  of 
civil  society.  The  natural  race-feeling  lays  the  foundation  also 
for  associations  resting  on  talents.  Through  variety  in  talents 
a  division  of  labour  is  naturally  brought  about ;  non  omnia 
possuvius  oynnes.  But  because  each  one,  in  order  to  subsist, 
needs  the  help  of  others,  as  the  others  need  his,  and  so  on  iu 
an  unending  circuit,  therefore  the  difference  of  talents  becomes 
a  strong  bond  of  union, — a  union  which  has  become  such 
deliberately.  The  fellowship  is  primarily  one  of  traffic,  which 
effects  an  exchange  of  the  products  of  labour.  Instead  of  the 
simple  having  and  possessing,  there  begins  a  mutual  giving 
and  receiving,  in  which  each  gains,  because  each  exchanges 
what  he  can  dispense  with  for  what  is  to  him  more  desirable. 
The  oldest  and  most  direct  form  of  traffic  is  barter  ;  but  there 


'TENDENCIES  TO  ASSOCIATION.  183 

is  soon  found  a  neutral  medium  of  value — money.  With  the 
traffic  there  become  connected  bargains  for  mutual  services  of 
a  personal  and  a  material  sort, — bargains  which  are  not  yet 
guarded  by  the  idea  of  right,  but  by  that  of  the  advantage  of 
all. 

But  as  from  the  diversity  of  talents,  so  also  from  their 
identity,  or  from  the  interests  arising  from  it,  there  result  a 
multitude  of  associations  or  unions  among  those  of  similar 
callings.  Here,  growing  out  of  the  difference  of  generations, 
belong  the  relations  of  master  and  apprentice,  of  teacher  and 
pupil,  that  is,  combinations  made  for  the  purpose  of  equaliza- 
tion by  those  who  are  in  the  relation  of  inequality.  Then 
again  there  are  combinations  of  those  in  the  relation  of 
equality,  e.g.  trades  associations ;  also  the  relations  of  service, 
so  far  as  these  depend  upon  compact, — in  compact  the  parties 
stand  over  against  each  other  as  equals, — and  so  far  as  they 
aim  at  giving  help  in  common  work;  or  again,  combinations 
of  those  who  are  alike  in  individual  tastes,  e.g.  combinations 
for  artistic  and  scientific  purposes  (so  far  as  science  and  art 
begin  to  become  active),  of  masters  among  themselves,  or 
of  learners  among  themselves, 

§  18.   The  Defects  of  the  Riidimentary  Civilisation  that  springs 
U2:)  naturally. 

The  natural  unity  of  the  faculties,  together  with  the  associa- 
tions which  they  evoke,  is  by  no  means  ethically  worth- 
less, but  still  is  in  itself  as  yet  only  ante-ethical.  It  is 
in  many  respects  imperfect,  and  exposed  to  dissolution 
and  confusion  through  caprice,  so  long  as  the  sound, 
normal  order  of  nature  is  not  sanctioned  and  preserved 
by  a  higher  principle. 

1.  We  have  seen  whither  human  nature  normally  tends, 
even  apart  from  the  really  moral  process.  We  have  seen  that 
it  leads  not  to  a  mere  division,  or  confusion,  of  the  faculties 
of  the  individual,  and  not  to  a  mere  separation  of  the  one 
species  into  a  multitude  of  antagonistic  individuals, — in  a 
word,  not  to  a  chaos,  but  to  a  connected  whole,  having 
adaptation  to  an  end,  and   exhibiting  marks  of  design.      In 


184     ^    §  18.    DEFECTS  OF  THE  NATURAL  CIVILISATION, 

the  single  natural  individuals  as  such,  and  in  their  relation 
to  one  another,  there  is  also  implanted  a  healthy,  efficient 
unifying  power,  which,  valuable  in  itself,  is  also  productive  of 
what  is  valuable. 

2.  But  if,  now,  we  consider  the  worth  of  the  products 
which  are  possible  at  this  stage,  two  views  are  to  be  excluded. 
(a)  A  spiritualistic  ethics,  which  despises  all  this,  because 
there  is  still  wanting  to  it  the  ethical  soul,  namely,  conscious 
freedom  of  will  and  a  moral  disposition.  Kant  goes  so  far 
that  he  treats  the  object  or  actual  thing  which  is  chosen  as 
■entirely  unessential  to  the  notion  of  moral  good.  He  requires 
that  this  be  disregarded  on  the  ground  that  the  essential 
thing  is  not  what  is  chosen,  but  how,  and  with  what  disposi- 
tion, the  choice  is  made.  Only  in  this  way  does  he  think  he 
■can  avoid  justification  by  works,  or  mere  legality.  Further- 
more, say  others,  what  is  done  without  conscious  free  choice 
■  can  be  called  only  a  product  of  nature,  consequently  falls 
entirely  outside  of  the  realm  of  morals,  and  is  without 
significance  for  an  ethical  world.  Both  views  involve  a 
:serious  error.  Against  Ivant  it  is  to  be  maintained  that  if 
the  morality  which  it  is  the  part  of  human  beings  to  reach 
depends  only  upon  a  good  disposition  or  a  good  will, — not  at 
all  upon  what  is  willed,  but  only  upon  how  one  wills, — this 
would  lead  us  to  the  principle  that  no  objective  thing  can  be 
morally  commanded,  but  that  rather  anything  can  be  chosen 
at  pleasure,  if  only  the  disposition,  intention,  or  end  be  good. 
But  this  is  a  Jesuitical  principle,  which  abandons  the  assump- 
tion of  all  necessary  connection  between  the  inward  disposition 
and  the  outward  work,  and  thus  imperils  the  whole  process  of 
building  up  a  moral  world.  It  must  rather  be  insisted  that 
choice  be  made  not  merely  in  the  right  moral  way,  but  also 
of  the  right  thing.  What  the  right  thing  is  could  not  be 
affirmed,  if  morality  hinged  merely  upon  that  most  inward  thing, 
the  bent  of  the  will.  But  in  that  case  the  personality  or  the 
ego  would  be  conceived  of  abstractly,  as  separated  from  all 
its  concrete  qualities,  by  which  alone,  nevertheless,  it  becomes 
a  living  being — one  that  not  merely  thinks,  but  also  chooses 
and  does  something.  With  nothing  but  a  disposition,  the 
person  would  remain  only  the  form  of  a  person,  always  and 
for  ever  willing  only  the  same  thing,  namely,  the  good  con- 


DEPRECIATION  AND  OVER-ESTIMATION  OF  IT.  185 

dition  of  the  will.  But  this  goodness  would  come  to  no 
development ;  the  disposition  would  remain  powerless  to 
effect  any  positive  ethical  manifestation. 

Accordingly  the  whole  domain  of  the  natural  exercise  of 
the  faculties  —  the  above  -  mentioned  spontaneous  products 
of  human  nature — has  after  all  a  great  significance  for  ethics. 
Although  it  antedates  real  morality,  it  is  yet  the  indispensable 
condition  {conditio  sine  qua  non)  of  the  building  up  of  a  moral 
world ;  it  is  the  scene  and  material  on  which  morality  operates  ; 
it  is  indispensable  to  the  manifestation,  and  to  the  reality, 
of  the  ethical  principle.  By  mere  thinking  we  could  not 
come  into  fellowship  with  others ;  in  order  to  this,  we  must 
utter  what  is  within  us.  But  this  is  not  possible  with- 
out a  physical  medium  by  means  of  which  minds  come  into 
contact  with  one  another.  Without  the  objective  reality 
constituted  by  the  natural  faculties  and  endowments  above 
considered,  there  would  be  wanting  both  to  the  individual 
and  to  the  race  the  needed  fulness  and  wealth, — the  supply 
of  means  for  mental  (and  also  moral  and  religious)  self- 
manifestation  and  expression.  And  in  the  fruits,  already 
considered,  of  the  natural  exercise  of  the  unifying  force,  so 
far  as  they  have  come  about  normally  by  virtue  of  innate 
impulses,  the  thought  of  the  Creator  has  continued  to  realize 
itself  He  has  thus  created  an  actual  order  of  the  world 
which,  although  not  as  yet  fixed  by  man's  free  act,  but  only 
through  his  instrumentality,  is  to  be  the  starting-point  of  the 
moral  process,  and  a  prototype  of  that  which  is  to  become  an 
ethical  product.  The  normal  unity,  as  well  as  the  variety,  of 
the  active  faculties  at  the  outset,  is  a  type  of  the  future  moral 
system.  To  preserve  these  faculties,  and  in  tiieir  normal 
connection  or  unity,  will  be  not  only  the  first,  but  also  a 
continual,  moral  duty.  From  the  high  position  which  we 
have  here  assigned  to  corporeality,  to  nature,  and  to  the 
subjection  of  it,  it  must  not,  however,  be  inferred  that  the 
significance  of  the  whole  ethical  process  through  which  man- 
kind passes — that  is,  the  significance  of  human  history — is 
merged  in  the  conquest  of  matter  and  in  the  subjugation  of 
nature. 

This  leads  {h)  to  the  more  frequent  error,  the  one  opposed 
to  the  spiritualistic,  that,  namely,  of  overvaluing  the  ivorth  of 


186  §  18.    DEFECTS  OF  THE  NATUKAL  CIVILISATION. 

this  natural  union  of  the  faculties  and  of  their  products.  Human 
life,  if  limited  to  these  natural  manifestations  iu  individuals 
and  society,  is  as  yet  very  incomplete.  It  is  often  asserted 
that  by  these  excellences,  without  any  moral  process,  an 
existence  noble  and  worthy  of  man  is  attainable  or  attained. 
But  although  the  products  of  these  faculties,  as  well  as  the 
secure  possession  of  them,  the  means  of  enjoyment,  etc.,  are 
certainly  good  things,  yet  they  are  in  themselves  only  of 
finite  value  ;  man  limited  to  them  would  be  with  them  alone 
not  as  yet  a  rational  being.  In  these  finite  spheres  there 
might,  it  is  true,  be  ability,  but  not  virtue.  Furthermore,  all 
these  things  are  in  themselves  as  yet  of  an  equivocal  nature. 
As  means,  they  are  subservient  to  the  best  disposition,  but  also 
just  as  much  to  the  worst ;  as  when,  e.g.,  the  ultimate  aim  is 
only  pleasure,  whether  coarser  or  more  refined,  but  an  aim 
having  absolute  worth  has  not  yet  appeared  above  the  moral 
horizon. 

If,  now,  all  this,  namely,  the  harmonious  play  of  the  finite 
faculties  iu  the  midst  of  the  plenitude  of  the  products  of 
culture,  is  regarded  as  the  destination  of  man,  as  a  false 
humanism  would  make  it,  then  we  have  hedonic  ethics;  and 
when  this  eudsemony,  these  objects  of  finite  worth,  are  made 
absolute,  there  is  presented  in  morals  the  complete  counter- 
part of  the  worship  of  false  gods  in  religion.  In  the  last 
analysis  that  would  be  only  selfishness,  and  we  should  get  no 
farther  ;  the  ruling  principle  would  be  only  shrewdness,  which 
weighs  or  regulates  the  pleasures  and  their  correct  succession, 
and  devotes  energy  to  the  procuring  of  the  means  for  gaining 
them.  Duty  would  be  as  much  a  tiling  out  of  the  question 
as  right  in  the  stricter  sense  would  be ;  duty  and  right  in 
that  case  would  together  sink  into  the  notion  of  that  which  is 
not  regulated  by  a  moral  standard.  Everything  which  pleases 
would  be  permitted  ;  ability,  power,  would  be  the  measure 
and  the  limit  of  lawfulness  ;  or  rather,  might  would  take  the 
place  of  right;  that  is,  in  that  case  caprice  would  have  the  freest 
scope.  And  even  if  to  this  caprice  limits  are  always  in  turn 
set  by  the  salutary  order  of  nature,  whose  violation  is  punished 
with  evil  by  a  reaction  of  that  salutary  nature,  yet  sagacity 
would  teach  one  to  avoid  such  evil ;  but  guilt,  punishment, 
and  sense  of  punishableness  would  be  out  of  the  question. 


MERELY  NATURAL  ASSOCIATIONS  INADEQUATE.  187 

3.  And  not  only  is  the  individual  life  of  the  natural  person, 
so  far  as  it  can  shape  itself  without  a  strictly  ethical  j^rocess, 
as  yet  very  imperfect,  but  so  also  are  those  communities  which 
are  formed  purely  spontaneously  by  natural  impulse  aided 
by  sagacity  and  intelligence.  Mere  sexual  or  conjugal  asso- 
ciation is  not,  properly  speaking,  wedlock ;  if  only  the  natural 
impulses,  of  a  physical  or  of  a  psychical  sort,  draw  indi- 
viduals together,  mutual  pleasure  and  complacency  will  pre- 
ponderate, and  will  be  the  real  bond ;  but  in  that  case 
the  consorts  are  means  for  each  othei",  and  not  an  end  in 
themselves, — not  the  other  ego,  but  only  the  extension  of 
each  one's  own  ego.  But  pleasure  is  an  equivocal  bond  of 
companionship ;  for  the  same  thing  which  now  connects  may 
at  another  time  work  to  separate.  If  elsewhere  there  is  more 
pleasure  to  be  hoped  for,  the  person  governed  by  physical  or 
psychical  affinity  will  turn  thither ;  and  this  would  not  even 
be  blameworthy,  if  the  mere  force  of  natural  impulses  may 
be  decisive,  and  no  healthful  order  exists  in  the  form  of 
duty  or  law.  If,  now,  we  imagine  that  in  the  case  of  botli 
consorts,  after  a  period  of  mutual  attractiveness,  the  same 
love  of  pleasure  which  joined  them  together  works  again 
to  sever  them,  then  the  family  also,  in  its  unity  and 
coherence,  is  destroyed  (Gen.  iv.  19,  vi.  1-6).  Where 
stability  is  wanting  to  the  marriage  bond,  there  can  be  only 
progeny,  proles;  but  the  family  relation  is  out  of  the 
question ;  just  as  is  the  case  with  brutes,  that  do  not  know, 
or  soon  forget,  to  what  parents  they  belong.  But  if  the 
family  relation  is  not  attained,  then  men  do  not  even  get  so 
far  as  to  form  tribes  and  tribal  regulations,  but  only  a  chaotic 
multitude,  a  conglomerate  human  horde,  which  will  never  be 
elevated  till  family  life,  above  all,  marriage,  stands  fast  as  a 
sacred  ordinance. 

Temperament  also,  and  natural  constitution,  cannot  as  such 
form  the  ground  of  a  stable  companionship.  For  here,  too,  it 
is  possible  that  another  person  is  sought  not  as  an  end  in 
himself,  but  only  as  a  means,  whether  it  be  for  entertainment 
and  enjoyment,  or  for  the  purpose  of  work.  This,  however,  does 
not  deserve  the  name  of  friendship,  but  only  of  comradeship, 
which  lasts  only  so  long  as  the  interests  do  not  cross,  but  run 
parallel.      The  same  holds  true,  finally,  of  the  unions  which 


188  §  18.    DEFECTS  OF  THE  NATURAL  CIVILISATION. 

are  formed  on  the  ground  of  difference,  or  resemblance,  of 
talents.  The  division  of  labour,  although  it  is  for  the  interest 
of  all,  can  be  so  made  that  indolence,  inordinate  love  of 
enjoyment,  or  greediness  gets  control  of  the  serving  and 
working  classes,  or,  on  the  other  hand,  so  that  the  faculties  of 
some  are  simply  taken  advantage  of  by  the  others.^  So,  too, 
traffic  in  itself  can  be  taken  into  the  service  of  selfishness, 
can  minister  to  fraud,  avarice,  and  dishonesty,  and  thus 
become  its  own  enemy.  For  where  credit  and  confidence  are 
wanting,  mercantile  intercourse  comes  to  a  standstill. 

Without  a  moral  process,  strictly  so  called,  a  each  of  justice 
and  a  State  are  out  of  the  question.  For  even  an  agreement 
presupposes  the  mutual  recognition  of  the  duty  to  abide  by 
it.  All  the  deficiencies,  perversions,  and  disorders  above  men- 
tioned become  unavoidable,  if  we  do  not  count  on  ethical 
forces  in  social  bodies,  and  do  not  feel  that  it  is  necessary 
to  care  for  these  forces,  which  after  all  are  in  the  interior 
being  what  the  spring  is  to  the  watch,  or  the  soul  to  the  body. 

4.  What  has  been  already  said  shows  that  the  unity  in  the 
faculties  of  individuals,  and  of  members  of  the  species,  which 
is,  as  it  were,  prearranged  in  the  salutary  order  of  nature,  can 
be  only  a  foretoken  of  the  true  ethical  unity,  but  not  this 
unity  itself;  it  is  rather  only  something  defective  and  even 
equivocal.  All  this  acquires  still  more  importance  from  the 
fact  that  in  man  instinct  does  not  have  the  same  power  and 
significance  as  in  brutes ;  while,  on  the  other  hand,  he 
has  the  power  of  voluntary  choice.  That  natural  salutary 
unifying  power  is  indeed  not  without  effect ;  it  has  as  its 
ally  also  the  arrangement  of  the  world,  which  manages  to 
make  even  egoism  its  ally,  so  far  forth  as  egoism  finds  its 
account,  in  the  long  run,  only  in  preserving  the  healthy 
order  of  nature.  But  it  is  not  a  compulsory  power ;  it  does 
not  draw  man  irresistibly  into  its  healthy  ways.  On  the 
other  hand,  sensuality  and  passion  make  men  imprudent  also, 
make  them  rush  inordinately  in  a  direction  that  for  the  time 
being  promises  the  greater  pleasure,  dazzled  by  which  they  forget 
tlie  consequences.  In  man,  indeed,  dwells  also  the  ability  to 
draw  himself  back  from  all  impulses  into  his  own  ego,  which 

^  E.g.  when  labour  is  taken  advantage  of  by  capital,  this  is  as  yet  a  state  of 
nature. 


DEFICIENCY  OF  HUMAN  INSTINCT.  189 

holds  concealed  an  indefinite  multitude  of  possibilities.  But 
without  law  we  yet  have  in  all  this  only  the  power  of  choice, 
which  is  able  to  break  away  from  the  sound  normal  impulse 
of  the  order  of  nature,  to  give  itself  on  the  other  hand  un- 
reservedly up  to  lawless  impulses,  and  thus  to  destroy  God's 
salutary  order  of  the  universe.  The  brute,  although  denied 
the  endowment  of  reason,  remains  in  his  healthy  natural  state 
by  the  force  of  instinct,  which  warns  against  what  is  injurious. 
For,  in  the  brute,  instinct  is,  as  it  were,  the  surrogate  of  reason, 
being  furnished  with  the  immediate  power  of  an  efficient 
impulse ;  it  is  for  the  brute,  as  it  were,  the  conscience  of  the 
collective  organism,  as  over  against  single  impulses  which 
would  lead  to  excess ;  although  even  the  brute  at  times  also 
makes  a  mistake.  But  in  man  that  overpowering  force  of 
instinct  is  wanting;  on  the  other  hand,  he  has  free  choice,  which 
is  not  obliged  to  make  itself  the  ally  of  the  unifying  tendency 
of  the  sound  order  of  the  universe,  as  over  against  the  sensual 
impulses  and  the  excitement  which  comes  from  the  diversified 
outward  world.  How  easily,  in  that  case,  it  may  happen, 
especially  when  one  persuades  himself  that  by  the  gratification 
of  his  own  bent  he  will  not  only  remain  well  off,  but  will 
augment  his  enjoyment  of  life,  that  this  unifying  tendency, 
since  it  does  not  work  compulsorily,  will  be  neutralized  both 
in  individuals  and  in  the  community  (Gen.  iii.  1  sqq.). 

According  as  free  choice  gives  the  reins  to  one  of  the 
impulses,  abnormalness  and  disorder  will  enter,  affecting  both 
individuals  and  communities ;  and  the  obverse  of  overpower- 
ing impulses  and  desires  in  certain  spheres  will  be  impotence 
with  reference  to  others.  The  disorder  will  involve  both  the 
physical  and  the  psychical  nature.  The  ungoverned  impulse 
for  possession  becomes  greed  and  avarice ;  the  unregulated 
impulse  for  honour  and  power  will,  in  the  form  of  pride, 
ambition,  and  thirst  for  dominion,  work  injury  to  others 
whom  it  brings  down.  The  consequence  in  the  case  of 
weaker  natures  will  be  envy,  servility,  and  cringing ;  while, 
in  the  case  of  stronger  natures,  pride  and  love  of  power  act 
contagiously ;  and  so  there  are  enkindled  strife  and  warfare, 
which  threaten  society  with  dissolution.  In  like  manner  the 
unbridled  impulse  for  enjoyment,  especially  the  ungoverned 
sexual  impulse,  destroys,  together  with  the  subject  of  it,  the 


190  §  IS.    DEFECTS  OF  THE  NATURAL  CIVILISATION. 

objective  advantages  of  companionship,  marriage,  family,  and 
social  life. 

In  a  word,  man  has,  answering  to  his  microcosmic  nature, 
such  many-sided  susceptibilities  and  impulses,  that,  especially 
considering  the  weakness  of  his  instinct,  he  could  not  find  his 
way  without  mistakes,  but  on  account  of  his  powerful  passions 
and  capacities  would  soon  become  a  chaos,  if  a  higher  light 
did  not  break  in  as  a  standard  of  order  and  harmony.  As  a 
onerely  finite  hcing  lie  is  not  a  inrfect  wlioU ;  he  is  too  much 
and  too  little,  so  that  it  is  impossible  that  at  this  stage  his 
creation  can  be  finished.  Endued  with  an  opulence  of 
faculties,  possessed  of  free  choice  in  alliance  with  cunning 
and  sagacity,  there  he  would  stand  as  an  enigmatical  terrible 
being,  almost  demoniacally  equipped  for  the  destruction  of 
the  world  and  of  himself,  if  there  were  no  higher  principle  for 
him,  able  to  guide  and  to  govern  his  physical  and  spiritual 
being,  namely,  fhe,  law  of  ethical  Good,  of  which  he  must  have 
knowledge,  unless  he  is  to  continue  a  mere  natural  creature. 
And  yet,  if  such  a  law  of  Good  were  simply  implanted  in 
him  as  a  higher  power  having  the  mastery  over  him,  he 
would  be  merely  a  natural  creature  of  a  higher  sort.  For 
then,  again,  he  could  not  participate  in  the  act  by  which  he 
is  constituted  an  ethical  being.  Accordingly,  the  equivocal 
unity  or  harmony  which  is  a  natural  growth  cannot  be  man's 
goal ;  nor  is  this  attained  by  the  simple  natural  exercise  of  his 
innate  faculties  ;  but  this  natural  stage  must  be  transcended 
by  means  of  the  moral  process.  This,  however,  comes  actually 
to  pass  only  by  man's  receiving  a  knowledge  of  obligation,  of 
moral  Good, — a  knowledge,  however,  which  does  not  operate 
compulsorily  upon  the  will  or  the  being. 


§  19.    SYNOPSIS  OF  THE  MORAL  PKOCESS.  191 


SECOND   DIVISION. 

OF  THE  MOKAL  PEOCBSS  IN  GENERAL,  OR  OF  THE  DIVINE  ORDER 
OF  THE  UNIVERSE  AS  THE  LAW  OF  ACTION  FOR  THE  MORAL 
FACULTIES. 

§19. 

On  the  basis  of  the  physical  and  mental  faculties  of  a 
common  and  of  an  individual  kind,  which  have  been 
considered  in  the  First  Division,  the  moral  process  is 
initiated.  This  is  done  by  the  separation  of  the  moral 
feeling,  which  is  the  beginning  of  the  rational  human 
existence,  into  moral  sense  and  impulse,  and  at  a  higher 
stage  into  actual  conscience  and  freedom.  This  separa- 
tion takes  place  in  order  that  the  objective  moral  law 
may  make  its  claims  in  a  clearly  conscious  way  upon 
the  free  will.  By  the  moral  process,  however,  the  simple 
or  natural  unity  of  the  rational  human  constitution  is 
broken  up  relatively  only  for  the  sake  of  seeking  a 
higher  form.  Accordingly  this  Division  is  subdivided 
into  the  doctrine  of  laio,  of  conscience,  and  oi  freedom. 

1.  The  necessity  of  an  ethical  process,  in  order  to  raise 
man  above  the  plane  of  mere  nature,  is  sufficiently  evident  from 
the  foregoing,  as  also  the  necessity  of  the  breaking  up  of  the 
original  unity  in  order  that  there  may  be  an  ethical  process. 
Three  factors  will  have  to  co-operate  in  order  to  constitute 
this  process.  The  first  is  the  law.  The  word  "  duty "  is 
often  used  as  synonymous  with  law ;  but  the  word  has 
reference  rather  to  some  single  concrete  thing,  having  more 
definite  regard  to  the  obligation  of  the  individual  than  the 
notion  of  law  has,  which  is  limited  to  pure  objectivity.  But 
the  necessity  of  taking  the  fi.rst  of  these  three  factors  as  a 
starting-point  will  be  plain  from  what  follows.  The  connecting 
of  ethics  with  the  idea  of  God,  which  we  found  to  be  necessary, 
has  fruitful  results  for  our  system  of  morals  only  when  we  take, 
as  the    starting-point  for   our   sketch  of  the  ethical  process, 


192  §  19.    SYNOPSIS  OF  THE  MORAL  PROCESS. 

nothing  else  than  the  moral  law.  It  might  be  thought, 
indeed,  that,  since  we  know,  of  morality  only  through  the 
moral  feeling,  conscience,  and  the  moral  consciousness,  there- 
fore the  moral  feeling,  etc.,  are  the  only  source  of  moral 
legislation ;  that  is,  that  the  moral  feeling,  conscience,  etc.,  are 
to  be  regarded  as  the  first,  fundamental  factor  of  moral 
existence  in  general.  But  such  a  view  regards  only  the 
subjective  process  rather  than  the  objective  fact  itself,  which 
is  that  neither  moral  feeling  nor  moral  sense  and  will  would 
be  possible  without  law ;  that,  rather,  man  without  it  would 
remain  shut  up  purely  to  finiteness.  If  we  do  not  go  back 
to  an  objective  moral  law  which,  because  it  is  in  and  of  itself 
true  and  certain,  is  independent  of  subjective  feeling,  sense, 
and  conscience,  then  these  things  themselves  would  be  in- 
correctly conceived.  Moral  feeling,  conscience,  etc.,  are  not 
absolutely  autonomous ;  only  in  case  they  were  so  could  they 
be  regarded  as  the  ultimate  source  of  the  moral  law.  On  the 
contrary,  the  objective  law  is  the  source  of  the  moral  feeling, 
sense,  and  conscience;  and  so  there  belongs  to  the  moral  feeling, 
sense,  and  conscience  itself,  the  consciousness  that  morality  is 
independent  of  the  knowledge,  yes,  of  the  being,  of  the  indi- 
vidual. The  objective  divine  reason  and  truth  it  is  which 
forms  itself  in  the  human  soul  and  first  brings  it  to  rational- 
ness.  The  law  is  made  secure  in  its  sacredness  and  objectivity 
only  by  our  treating  it  in  its  connection  with  the  ethical  idea 
of  God  as  the  first  fundamental  factor  of  the  ethical  process. 
"  Law  is  the  rock  on  which  ethics  rests,  and  it  reaches  down  to 
the  lowest  depths."  ^  Of  it,  therefore,  our  first  section  is  to 
treat.  But  not  only  the  objectivity  of  this  law  must  by  all 
means  be  secured,  but  also  its  entrance  into  the  spirit, 
primarily  into  the  intelligence,  which,  recognising  morality  in 
its  truth  and  absolute  authority,  brings  it  home  to  the  will. 
There  must  be  implanted  in  us,  as  our  own,  a  knowledge  o^ 
the  Good  as  such,  or  as  the  truth ;  without  this  knowledge 
we  could  not  do  anything  for  the  reason  that  it  is  good,  but 
only  for  other,  that  is,  non-moral,  reasons.  But  like  human 
development  in  general,  so  also  this  apprehension  of  the 
divine  law  is  gained  only  gradually. 

2.  The   commencement   of    the   process   is   in   the    moved 

1  Schniid,  ChristL  Sittenlehre,  p.  346. 


LAW,  MORAL  FEELING,  CONSCIENCE,  FKEEDOM,  193 

feeling,  in  which  are  inchided  moral  cognition  and  volition, 
at  first  still  in  undivided  unity.  The  moral  feeling  is 
(§  12.  4)  a  feeling  of  that  which  has  absolute  worth  as 
addressed  to  the  will ;  and  in  it  is  involved  (a)  the  being 
affected  by  the  ethical  idea  as  one  which  demands  reverence 
and  obedience.  And  the  being  thus  affected  is,  moreover,  not 
a  merely  subjective  sensation ;  the  moral  feeling  is  a  feeling 
for  something  objective  and  in  itself  sacred.  If,  now,  the 
object  of  the  moral  feeling  is  fixed  by  itself,  that  is,  if  the 
thing  felt  to  be  of  worth  is  grasped  as  such  by  the  cognitive 
faculty,  then  there  arises  a  moral  conception :  and  the  feeling 
becomes  a  sense  of  what  is  sacred  and  morally  imperative,  as 
distinguished  from  the  Nefas.  (b)  But,  on  the  other  hand,  there 
is  in  the  moral  feeling,  besides  the  perception  of  dependence 
upon  a  necessary  something,  upon  a  higher,  sacred  order,  also 
a  germinant  consciousness  of  freedom.  For  in  the  moral 
feeling  there  is  an  ideal  law,  together  with  inward  delight  in 
it ;  but  the  ideal  feeling  of  delight  is  the  feeling  of  an  at  least 
possible  freedom.  The  feeling,  being  moral,  presages  the 
gaining  of  a  higher  existence  through  the  working  of  the 
power  by  which  the  feeling  is  stirred.  The  beginning  of 
freedom,  however,  is  contained  in  impulse,  and,  further  on, 
in  the  will.  Thus  the  analysis  of  the  moral  feeling  shows 
the  possibility  of  its  transition  into  moral  sense  and  impulse. 

3.  But  the  breaking  up  of  the  original  unity  is  also  necessary. 
Feeling  is  in  the  first  instance  only  a  simple  primary  modifi- 
cation \_unmittelbare  Bestimnithcit]  in  man,  neither  posited  nor 
shaped  by  his  will.  But  in  the  moral  world  the  will,  the 
self-determination,  forms  the  centre ;  and  this  holds  true  even 
in  relation  to  receptivity  and  feeling,  for  there  is  also  such  a 
thing  as  vMling  to  be  moved  and  determined.  But  the 
will  must  ivill  something,  and  this  can  come  to  it  only  through 
the  intelligence,  which  sets  before  the  will  the  object  to  be 
chosen.  Therefore,  in  order  that  there  may  be  a  moral  process 
of  the  will,  there  must  be  developed,  first  of  all,  moral  intel- 
ligence, i.e.  moral  sense,  and  further  on,  conscience.  Thus 
the  object  confronts  the  will,  is  held  before  it  as  something 
to  be  done.  If  the  will  were  determined  merely  by  the 
feelings,  the  will  would  be  without  clear  consciousness,  hence 
also   without   freedom.     Therefore   cognition  and   will   must 

N 


194  §  19.    SYNOPSIS  OF  THE  MORAL  PE0CES3. 

separate  ;  this  is  the  condition  of  their  independent  develop- 
ment. The  next  thing  is  the  separation  of  the  moral  feeling 
into  moral  sense  and  impulse.  But  moral  cognition,  in  the 
form  of  a  mere  sense  and  vague  apprehension,  is  not  yet 
objectively  definite  and  sure  enough ;  no  less  true  is  it  that 
the  will,  so  long  as  it  is  simple  impulse,  is  too  much  moved 
by  feeling  and  nature.  Hence  the  independent  development 
of  both  must  proceed  farther,  till  the  moral  sense  and  vague 
apprehension  become  clear  and  fixed  conscience,  and  till  the 
moral  impulse  becomes  freedom  of  will. 

Thus  the  moral  feeling  is  separated  into  the  two  poles  of  the 
morally  necessary  [i.e.  imperative,  TPt.]  and  the  morally  free, 
both  of  which,  however,  stand  in  intimate  relation  to  each 
other.  Conscience  is  a  knowledge  of  that  which  is  necessary ; 
of  that,  however,  which  is  morally  necessary,  addressed  to 
freedom ;  that  is,  it  recognises  freedom,  and  even  incites  to 
moral  self-determination,  but  does  not  necessitate.  Eather,  as 
that  which  is  morally  necessary  is  independent,  in  relation 
to  that  which  is  free,  so  the  free  is  independent,  as  over 
against  the  morally  necessary,  and  exists  already  in  the  form 
of  power  of  choice,  before  all  higher  development  of  the 
intelligence.  But,  as  we  soon  see,  it  is  only  through  the 
consciousness  of  moral  necessity  that  freedom  gets  its  higher 
meaning,  and  is  given  to  itself  as  the  power  of  a  decision  of 
infinite  importance  ;  and  now  freedom,  whether  it  will  or  will 
not,  must  enter  into  a  relation  either  negative  or  positive  to 
that  which  is  morally  necessary.  For  even  the  failure  to 
make  an  unconditionally-required  decision  is  itself  a  decision. 
But  with  the  decision  the  moral  process  comes  into  existence. 

If,  on  the  other  hand,  the  character  of  the  decision  were 
not  left  to  free  choice,  but  were  forced  upon  one,  for  example, 
by  the  necessitating  power  of  the  consciousness  of  what  is 
morally  right,  then,  again,  the  stage  of  morality  would  not  be 
reached ;  moral  responsibility  and  moral  personality  would 
still  be  unattained.  If,  for  example,  even  love  to  God  were 
fixed  by  God  without  possibility  of  resistance,  then  such  love 
would  have  no  moral  worth.  To  this  actual  antithesis  of 
moral  necessity  and  freedom,  which  is  in  no  way  a  contradic- 
tion, every  rational  nature  comes ;  thus  even  Christ  speaks  of 
an  evToKrj  of  the  Father,  a  moral  hec,  as  applying  to  Him ;  and 


THE  DIVINE  AGENCY  CONTINUOUS.  195 

tlie  knowledge  of  this  duty  is  the  knowledge  which  conscience 
has.  Accordingly,  it  cannot  be  said  with  the  little  book 
Deutsche  Thcologie  [Thcologia  Germanicct],  that  only  we  men 
have  conscience,  but  Christ  and  Satan  have  none.  This 
would  be  correct  only  if  conscience  were  either  the  effect 
of  sin,  like  the  so-called  evil  conscience,  or  the  cause  of 
sin.  The  antithesis  spoken  of  between  freedom  and  moral 
necessity  in  no  way  involves  even  the  least  element  of 
contradiction  between  the  two. 

4.  On  the  other  hand,  the  rational  constitution,  as  it 
actually  exists,  must  not  be  deistically  conceived  of  as  a  mere 
self-unfolding  of  the  human  faculties  without  the  continued 
operation  of  God.  Eather  God's  causality  is  operative  in  it. 
His  creative  will  it  is  which  first  perfectly  realizes  the  moral 
constitution,  since  He  clearly  and  vividly  evokes  also  the 
consciousness  of  the  objective  moral  requirement.  And  with 
reference  to  the  will  also  the  deistic  view  is  none  the  less 
to  be  excluded.  The  power  to  exercise  a  good  volition 
comes  from  above ;  by  God  and  His  revelation  that  which  is 
good  can  be  put  before  man  in  an  alluring  and  attractive, 
although  not  in  a  compulsory,  way.  There  is  besides  this 
the  connection  of  the  feelings  and  the  will.  This  connection 
continues  on  also  in  the  moral  process,  and  like  a  soul,  like 
an  ideal  inspiring  delight,  can  permeate  thought  and  volition ; 
and  out  of  the  acts  of  thinking  and  willing  there  must  be 
always  a  return  into  feeling  again.  But  in  feeling  the  soul 
in  its  totality  is  capable  of  being  affected  or  determined  by 
God,  and  the  human  will  can  doubtless  participate  in  this ; 
it  can  cJioose  to  let  itself  be  determined  by  God  and  His 
Spirit.  Therefore  in  the  feelings  is  to  be  found  the  inmost 
source  whence,  when  the  intellect  is  darkened  and  the  will  is 
powerless  and  bound,  help  can  still  come  to  man.  There,  too, 
the  longing  after  light  and  after  emancipation  from  bondage 
is  still  possible,  and  it  can  impel  man  to  apply  to  the  divine 
source  of  life,  in  order  tliat  human  impotence  may  be  removed 
by  power  from  on  high. 

Note. — In  accordance  with  what  has  been  said,  our  Division 
subdivides  itself  into  three  Sections  :  the  doctrine  of  the  Divine 
Law  ;  of  the  suhjective  Apprehension  of  the  Daw,  or  of  the  Con- 
science ;  and  of  Freedom. 


196     §  20.  god's  nature  the  source  of  the  moral  law. 

FIEST    SECTION. 

the  binding  character  of  the  objective  moral  law. 

§  20. 

The  good  which  is  eternally  realized  in  God's  being  and  will 
He  wills  as  the  law,  or  binding  rule,  or  obligation,  for 
the  world.  The  law  of  the  moral  world  is  essentially 
distinguished  from  the  law  of  nature  by  its  character  of 
intrinsic  necessity,  absoluteness,  and  universality.  As  an 
obligating  power,  it  embraces  the  faculties  of  knowledge 
and  volition  and  the  state  of  being, — both  what  is 
common  to  all  and  what  is  peculiar  to  each, — yet  not 
without  adapting  itself  to  individuals. 

Cf.  Schleiermacher's  treatises  on  NaUirgcsctz  and  Sittengesetz, 
and  also  on  Das  Erlauhte,  Schmid,  Dc  notione  legis,  and  Sitten- 
Ichre,  140,  156,  260-280,  345  sqq.  Heinrich  Merz,  Sijstcm  der 
christl.  Sittenlelire  nach  den  Grundsdtzen  des  Frotcstantismus  im 
Gcgcnsatz  zum  Katholicismus,  1841.  [Martenseu,  Christl.  Etliik, 
3rd  ed.  i.  441  sq.,  ii.  1,  p.  25  sq.  Zeller,  Ueher  Begriff  v.nd 
Begrilndung  der  sittlicJicn  Gcsctze,  1882.  Ueher  das  Kant'sche 
Moralprincip  und  den  Gcgensatz  formaler  und  inaterialer  Moral- 
principien,  1879.  (Both  treatises  now  in  the  third  volume  of 
his  Vortrdgc  und  Ahhandlungen,  1884.)  Kostlin,  Jahrhiicher 
fur  deidsche  Theologie,  vol.  xiii.  p.  383  sq.,  xiv.  pp.  25  sq., 
464  sq.  Studien  ilhcr  das  Sittengesetz.  Cf.  also.  Die  Aiifgahe 
der  christl.  Ethik,  in  the  Studien  und  Kritihen,  1879,  p.  581  sq. 
Cf.  note,  p.  204.— Ed.] 

1.  Conscience  is  not  the  ground,  but  the  perception,  of  the 
moral  law  ;  the  iwincipiutn  not  cssendi,  but  cognoscendi.  It  is 
God  who  implants  the  principle  of  morality  in  the  human 
spirit,  and  that  necessarily  only  as  an  idea.  God's  creative 
activity  {voluntas)  is  not  to  be  identified  with  His  legislative 
activity  (prcecepttim).  A  new  life  of  love  could  not  be 
directly  posited  as  a  finished  thing,  for  a  world  different 
from  God  was  to  move  freely  and  with  an  activity  of  its 
own.  The  creative  will  could  at  the  outset  implant  only  the 
possibility,  not  the  actuality,  of  the  good.  Nevertheless,  it 
cannot  be  said  that  the  good  is  not  existent.     Eather,  because 


CONSCIENCE  NOT  THE  GROUND,  BUT  THE  PERCEPTION,  OF  LAW.    197 

it  has  its  reality  in  God,  it  acquires  through  God  an  exist- 
ence for  or  in  the  intelligence  of  man.  This  existence  is  ideal 
at  first,  being  the  thought  of  that  which  ought  to  be  in  the 
world,  that  is,  law.  Since  now  God  is  in  His  essence  holy- 
love,  it  may  also  be  said,  according  to  this  derivation  of  law, 
that  it  is  nothing  else  than  holy  love  as  obligatory  (Matt.  xxii. 
37  sqq. ;  Eom.  xiii.  10).  God,  who  is  love,  wills  that  He,  as 
love,  be  acknowledged  and  have  sway. 

By  thus  going  back  to  God,  not  only  is  the  objective 
character  of  the  law,  independent  of  all  subjectivity,  secured, 
but  also  the  character  of  necessity,  absoluteness,  and  uni- 
versality is  conferred  upon  it.  In  these  three  predicates 
the  difference  between  the  moral  law  and  everything  physical 
is  expressed,  and  especially  opposition  to  all  utilitarian 
theories  of  morals.  The  moral  law  is  to  be  derived  neither 
from  divine,  nor  from  human,  arbitrary  choice,  but  is  a  reve- 
lation of  God  proceeding  from  His  legislative  will.  It 
demands  the  realization  of  the  divine  image  for  which  man  is 
created.  "  Be  ye  holy,  for  I  am  holy  "  (Ex.  xix.  6  ;  Lev.  xi. 
44 ;  Matt.  v.  48).  It  proceeds  from  God's  spiritual  essence 
(Eom.  vii.  14).  Hence  it  is  eternal,  and  can  never  be 
changed  by  human  will,  being  the  mirror  of  the  divine 
essence.  Only  so  does  the  question,  what  is  good,  cease  to 
be  merely  a  historical  question,  dependent  upon  external 
authorities ;  the  good  has  its  own  authority  with  itself  and  in. 
itself.  This  the  Evangelical  Church,  conscious  of  its  own 
principles,  in  opposition  to  the  ecclesiastical  positivism  of 
Eome,  has  always  held  fast.  The  Formula  Concordice  ^  says  : 
Zcx  proprie  est  doctrina  divina,  in  qua  justissima  et  immutahilis 
dei  voluntas  revelatur.  But  Melanchthon  says  not  merely 
that  law  is  the  divine  will,  but  also  lex  dei  est  sapicntia  sterna 
et  immutata  in  dec  et  norma  justitice  in  voluntate  dei,  which 
brings  to  mind  the  doctrine  of  Augustine,  that  the  law  has  its 
ultimate  root  in  God's  sapientia  jjrima,  in  which  also  lie  the 
principles  of  all  arts  and  sciences,  as  well  as  of  life,  that  is, 
the  principles  of  logic  and  of  mathematics,  of  assthetics  and 
of  ethics.  This  law  now,  immutable  in  God,  transscribitur  in 
sapientes  animos. 

2.  When  we  pass  on  to  the  separate  characterizations  of 

1  592.  3  ;  713.  17. 


1{>8     §  20.  god's  nature  the  source  of  the  moral  law. 

the  moral  law  as  to  its  formal  side,  the  first  attribute  ^ve  have 
to  consider  is  (a)  necessity.  There  are,  it  is  true,  many  kinds 
Off  necessity.  There  is  physical  necessity,  which  rules  in 
nature,  and  to  which  belong  coercion  and  force.  But  this  is 
out  of  the  question  here,  because  the  ethical  realm  claims 
freedom  for  itself.  A  second  sort  is  logical  necessity,  or  the 
necessity  of  the  sequence  of  ideas.  Of  this  also  it  is  to  be 
said,  that  it  does  not  concern  us  here,  because  it  belongs  to  it 
irresistibly  to  determine  thought  alone,  but  not  the  will  and 
the  being.  The  moral  law  is  compatible  with  freedom.  Its 
necessity  lies,  in  the  first  place,  in  its  origin,  i.e.  in  the  fact 
that  it  emanates  from  God,  and  that  not  fortuitously,  but  by 
virtue  of  the  divine  nature.  But  just  on  that  account  is  to 
be  ascribed  to  it  a  necessity  as  to  its  intrinsic  essence ;  while 
in  the  case  of  everything  physical,  even  when  necessity 
governs  its  movements,  it  may  yet  be  asked.  To  what  pur- 
pose ?  It  is  not  fitted  to  be  an  end  in  itself,  but  only  a 
means.  Its  necessity,  therefore,  is  only  a  hypothetical  one, 
conditioned  upon  something  else,  which  is  the  end.  And 
similarly  also  logical  necessity  is  a  hypothetical  one,  inasmuch 
as  the  consequence  holds  only  in  case  the  proposition  from 
which  it  flows  is  granted ;  but  in  the  proposition  it  is  by 
no  means  needful  that  there  inhere  an  intrinsic  necessity, 
that  of  being  an  end  in  itself.  Morality,  on  the  other  hand, 
is  in  itself  absolutely  valuable  and  good ;  in  the  conception  of 
it  the  inquiry  after  the  Why  must  cease ;  it  has  thus  a  teleo- 
logical  necessity.  Nevertheless  it  is  law,  namely,  the  law  of 
freedom,  and  therein  also  different  from  natural  law.  It  is 
]iecessary  to  moral  law  not  to  necessitate,  not  to  compel ;  but, 
on  the  other  hand,  no  rational  being  can  evade  it.  It  is  of 
force  for  man,  whether  he  will  or  not,  because  it  is  in  itself 
good  and  necessary.  That  relation  of  law  to  the  person,  now, 
by  which  a  binding  force  is  imposed  upon  him,  is  called  ohliga- 
tion,  while  the  thing  as  commanded  is  called  duty,  whether  it 
only  seeks  to  be  realized,  or  whether  it  is  already  in  process 
of  realization ;  for  obligatory  actions  also  are  by  many 
moralists  called  duty,  as  by  Eothe,  Werner,  and  Bruch. 

(&)  To  the  law  belongs,  in  the  second  place,  the  character 
of  absoluteness.  It  has  for  rational  beings  not  merely  a  hypo- 
thetical simificance  :  for  although  it  also  includes  that  which 


NECESSITY  AND  ABSOLUTENESS  OF  THE  LAW.      199 

is  subordinate,  as,  for  example,  the  means  to  an  end,  yet  on 
account  of  this  end  what  is  subordinate  participates  in  the 
absoluteness.  In  this  absoluteness  is  guarded  all  that  is  true 
in  Kant's  Categorical  Imperative.  There  is  something  absolute 
for  the  will,  which  has  absolutely  the  right  to  demand  recogni- 
tion, and  which  cannot  be  willing  not  to  be  and  to  have 
validity,  if  man  would  be,  or  would  remain,  rational.  From 
its  absoluteness  follows  the  intrinsic  necessity  of  the  law  to 
obligate  absolutely.  This  obligatory  power  it  owes  purely  to  its 
innate  right,  its  intrinsic  majesty.  The  recognition  of  it  is  no 
merit,  but  a  duty  ;  the  failure  to  recognise  it,  however,  is  guilt. 

This  character  of  al)soluteness  comes  especially  to  view 
vv'hen  we  contrast  the  moral  law  with  natural  law.  Schleier- 
macher,  in  his  celebrated  academical  treatise  in  the  year  1828, 
sets  forth  with  acuteness  the  relationship  of  the  two,  but  not 
also  their  unlikeness.  Even  nature,  he  says,  has  a  law,  an 
inner  force  and  rule,  for  its  growth  and  formation.  Natural 
things,  too,  do  not  always  turn  out  according  to  this  rule, 
as  we  see  is  the  case  also  in  the  human  world.  Yet,  he  says, 
in  nature,  too,  the  ideal  type  remains,  to  which  she  seeks  to 
conform,  even  though  through  obstacles.  So  also,  he  says, 
there  is  in  man  an  ideal  type,  a  standard  which  seeks  to 
regulate  the  moral  life,  although  the  world  of  reality  acts  as 
an  obstruction.  The  moral  law  is  for  Schleiermacher  simply  a 
higher  form  of  natural  law,  that  is,  a  law  for  intelligent  beings. 

But  just  this  makes  a  deeper  difference  than  Schleier- 
macher admits,  as  relates  both  to  substance  and  to  form. 
As  a  spiritual,  that  is,  rational  being,  man  is  open  to  that 
which  has  i7hfinite  worth.  Nature  has  objects  of  only  finite, 
not  absolute,  worth.  The  worth  of  the  forms  it  takes  depends, 
in  the  last  analysis,  upon  that  for  which  nature  exists  or  is 
the  means,  namely,  moral  good,  which  absolutely  ought  to  be ; 
and  for  this  reason  the  moral  law  alone,  so  far  as  relates  to  the 
form,  makes  an  absolute  requirement.  Nature  may  indeed 
succumb  to  obstacles  and  produce  ugly  things ;  still  the 
unpesthetic  is  not  utterly  objectionable,  as  wickedness  is.  In 
addition  to  this  there  is  the  further  difference  that  the 
spiritual  nature  of  man  is  duplex,  consisting  of  intelligence 
and  will.  The  ideal  type,  in  the  case  of  man,  must,  before 
it  passes  over  into  actual  being,  first  be  mediated  by  the  will ; 


200    §  20.  god's  nature  the  souece  of  the  moral  law. 

and  to  that  end  this  norm  at  first  appears  only  as  an  idea 
addressed  to  the  intelligence,  and  seeking  entrance  into  the 
will.  In  nature,  on  the  other  hand,  the  ideal  norm  does  not 
as  such  address  itself  to  the  will,  but  passes  over  straightway 
into  reality,  even  though  amidst  outward  obstacles.  In  man 
so  little  does  this  transition  take  place  immediately,  that  he 
can  by  his  will  oppose  even  inward  obstacles  to  it.  In  man 
a  purely  ideal  existence  of  the  good  precedes  its  realization, 
— it  is  an  esse  in  the  intelligence,  while  at  the  same  time  it  is 
a  nondum  esse  in  the  will.  There  "prceceptum  and  voluntas  do 
not  coincide.  Moreover,  although  nature  has  its  own  law 
different  from  the  law  of  morality,  yet  this  does  not  rend 
asunder  the  unity  of  the  world.  For  the  two  are  not  co- 
ordinate, but  the  moral  law  is  the  higher,  and  by  virtue  of 
its  character  of  absoluteness  it  obligates  and  authorizes  us  to 
treat  everything,  even  nature,  as  being  for  the  sake  of  morality 
and  intended  to  subserve  it. 

(c)  The  third  attribute  is  the  universality  of  the  moral  law. 
This  has  reference  to  the  circuit  which  it  embraces  with 
its  claim.  This  predicate  of  universality  might  be  questioned, 
since  God's  will  embraces  not  merely  the  moral  world,  which 
is  only  for  rational  beings,  but  nature  also  ;  by  the  moral 
law  the  unity  of  the  world  might  even  seem  to  be  threatened. 
But  the  natural  world  was  not  decreed  as  a  finished  whole,  as 
a  kingdom  which  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  moral  world. 
On  the  contrary,  the  very  fact  that  the  moral  law  is  a  law 
of  the  spirit,  implies  that  the  spirit  is  that  which  is  to  rule 
over  nature  —  that  nature  is  not  independent,  still  less, 
dominant  over  the  spirit ;  hence  the  moral  law  is  just  that 
which  guarantees  the  unity  of  the  world.  Hence  it  may  be 
said,  that  morality  is  the  supreme  universal  law,  which 
includes  in  itself,  and  disposes  for  itself,  the  whole  universe — 
the  law  which  assigns  to  everything,  even  to  nature,  its  proper 
place.  To  be  sure,  the  law  with  its  binding  power  addresses 
itself  immediately  and  directly  only  to  rational  beings.  But 
indirectly  it  embraces  nature  also.  For  not  merely  is  it 
man's  part  to  have  dominion  over  nature,  but  also  nature  is 
the  indispensable  means  of  all  concrete  moral  relations,  since 
without  it  they  could  not  at  all  exist.  So  far  forth  it  may  be 
said  that  the  moral  law  is  nothiucr  else  than  the  ideal  imago 


UNIVEKSALITY  OF  THE  LAW.  201 

of  the  world  itself  as  it  should  be,  i.e.  as  it  should  become 
through  the  will  governed  by  moral  considerations. 

Of  this  ideal  of  the  world  as  to  its  contents  we  have  to 
speak  in  the  Third  Division  ;  here  we  treat  only  of  its  formal 
side,  or  of  obligation.  As  applied  to  man,  now,  the  univer- 
sality of  the  moral  law  implies  the  universality  of  the  obliga- 
tion which  it  imposes  ;  and  this  relates  (1)  to  all  earthly 
rational  beings  (mankind),  (2)  to  every  moment  of  their  con- 
scious existence,  (3)  to  all  their  powers,  but  in  such  a  manner 
that  the  person,  this  unit,  is  always  that  which  is  placed 
under  obligation/  The  law  draws  all  the  powers  into  its 
binding  power ;  its  validity  for  them  is  unconditional,  and  it 
tolerates  no  restrictions  within  the  rational  being  of  man. 
Together  with  the  reason  the  ethical  idea  awakes  in  man ; 
but  rationalness  is  designed  to  be  in  man  a  permanent 
state.  It  demands  to  have  not  a  merely  temporary  exist- 
ence in  him,  not  merely  to  shine  into  him  from  time  to  time, 
and  at  other  times  to  let  him  keep  becoming  a  brute  again,  to 
which,  as  it  were,  everything  is  allowed  that  lies  in  his  power 
and  that  his  impulse  leads  him  to.  On  the  contrary,  the 
ethical  idea,  when  once  it  has  risen  in  one's  consciousness, 
involves  the  demand  that  the  whole  conscious  life,  without 
exception,  be  continually  subject  to  it ;  and  against  this  claim 
neither  the  weakness  nor  limitation  of  man  on  the  one  hand, 
nor  the  superior  force  of  nature  on  the  other,  can  make  any 
valid  protest. 

From  the  foregoing  it  follows  that  the  moral  law  in  its 
way  embraces  also  the  other  fundamental  forms  in  which  the 
moral  element  exists,  viz.  virtue  and  the  highest  good  ;  but  it 
embraces  them  in  its  character  of  a  requirement.  It  insists 
not  only  on  being  in  the  intelligence,  but  also  on  dwelling 
and  ruling  in  the  will ;  it  demands  an  existence  even  in  the 
fundamental  disposition,  and  requires  that  the  ethical  faculty, 
or  virtue,  shall  not  remain  a  latent  faculty,  but  shall 
manifest  itself  actively.  It  demands  that  the  good,  by  means 
of  good  or  right  actions  and  works,  shall  acquire  a  subjective- 
objective  form  of  existence,  that  is,  shall  attain,  in  the 
character  of  the  highest  good,  a  fixed  habitual  state,  while 
yet  it  remains  a  living  power.     The  moral  law  requires  that 

^  Matt,  xxii.  37  Sf^q.  ;  Gal.  vi.  2 ;  Rom.  xiii,  8  sq. 


202      §  21.  IIEFUTATION  OF  EREONEOUS  VIEWS  OF  THE  MORAL  LAW. 

the  good  exist  in  all  these  three  forms,  and  that  there  be  a 
progress  from  one  to  the  other.  It  insists  upon  being  the 
controlling  centre  of  one's  thoughts,  words,  volitions,  actions, 
and  works, — of  his  feelings,  his  states,  and  his  activities. 
It  insists  on  being  continuous  and  omnipresent  in  the  human 
life. 

But  although  the  moral  law  embraces  everything,  yet  this 
does  not  require  an  absolute  uniformity  of  the  world  or  of  the 
activity  of  the  will.  Love  must  indeed  be  the  ruling  prin- 
ciple in  all  the  functions  ;  but  the  manifestation  of  it  must 
be  governed  objectively  by  the  circumstances,  subjectively  by 
the  faculties,  of  the  individuals.  On  the  other  hand,  every- 
thing in  its  way  is  wholly  embraced  by  the  moral  obliga- 
tion. In  this  respect  the  law  divides  itself  into  many  members  ; 
and,  being  thus  multiform,  it  comprehends  the  world,  primarily 
man,  and  indirectly  also  nature. 

Against  this  statement  of  the  characteristics  of  the  moral 
law,  objection  is  made  from  various  sources. 

§  21.    Tlic  Denial  of  the  Formal  Fiindamcntal  Attributes  of  the 

Moral  Law. 

We  must  set  aside  not  only  the  denial  of  one  or  another  of 
the  above-developed  fundamental  attributes  of  the  moral 
law,  but  also  the  distinction  between  half,  or  imperfect, 
duty,  and  whole,  or  perfect,  duty.  We  must  also  reject 
the  Catholic  distinction  between  an  imperative  and  a 
merely  advisory  part  of  the  moral  law  {Consilia  Evan- 
gelica),  together  with  the  assumption  that  there  are 
actions  which  are  morally  indifferent,  or  merely  per- 
missible, and  not  obligatory,  for  the  person  in  question. 
Finally,  We  must  reject  also  the  doctrine  that  the  duties 
of  love  stand  higher  than  the  duties  of  right,  and  are 
therefore  to  be  preferred.  On  the  other  hand,  the 
universality  of  the  moral  law,  the  subsumption  of  the 
whole  life  and  of  all  one's  powers  under  the  moral 
order,  must  of  course  not  be  so  understood  as  that  all 
the  duties  which  form  the  contents  of  the  moral  law 


DENIAL  OF  THE  ABSOLUTENESS  AND  UNIVEESALITY  OF  LAM'.     203 

unconditionally  require  to  be  fulfilled  by  all  men  and  in 
every  moment  of  their  life  alike,  so  that  all  would  be 
under  obligation  to  do  the  same  thing  at  all  times.  Eatlier, 
the  universality  of  the  moral  law  means  only  that  the 
law,  in  itself  consisting  of  various  members,  embraces  the 
whole  world  with  its  many  members,  so  that  each 
individual,  with  his  own  peculiarities,  has  at  all  times, 
in  the  moral  organism  of  the  world,  his  special  place 
assigned  to  him,  which  he,  in  due  regard  to  his 
circumstances,  is  to  occupy  with  his  powers  in  such  a 
way  as  shall  accomplish  the  most  for  the  progressive 
realization  of  the  Good,  or  of  the  kingdom  of  God. 

1.  Tlie  objective  necessity  of  the  moral  law  follows  at  once 
from  the  idea  of  moral  goodness,  and  is  consequently  ques- 
tioned only  by  utilitarians  on  the  one  hand,  and  by  Scotists 
on  the  other ;  the  former  making  the  moral  law  to  be 
dependent  on  subjective  caprice,  the  latter,  on  the  snpremum 
liherum  arhitrium  of  God. 

More  frequent,  however,  is  the  denial  of  the  absolute- 
ness and  universality  of  the  moral  law.  Against  the  doctrine 
that  moral  goodness  has  an  absolutely  obligatory  claim,  and 
one  that  affects  the  whole  personal  life,  the  Roman  Catliolic 
Church  sets  up  the  proposition,  that  there  is  that  which  is 
morally  good,  but  which  nevertheless  is  not  unconditionally 
commanded  or  universally  binding.  The  meaning  is  not  that 
there  is  moral  excellence,  which  yet  must  not  be  treated  as  a 
debt  due  or  as  a  legal  duty  ;  for  example,  there  is  much 
which  is  in  itself  good,  but  which  the  State  cannot  and  ought 
not  to  carry  through  by  force  ;  deeds  of  benevolence  it  must 
leave  to  the  free  will.  Nor  is  the  meaning  that  there  is  a 
sphere  of  individuality  (§  13-16),  which  others  can  never 
wholly  see  through,  for  which  reason  they  also  cannot  define 
how  the  individual  in  all  particulars  must  act  in  order  to 
comply  with  the  duty  which,  though  absolute,  yet  adapts 
itself  to  individuals.  The  Eoman  Catholic  Church,  as  we 
know,  is  not  very  indulgent  to  the  peculiarities  of  indivi- 
duals. The  meaning  rather  is,  that  there  is  a  kind  of  good- 
ness which,  even  in  the  view  of   God  and  the   enlightened 


204      §  21.  EEFUTATION  OF  ERKONEOUS  VIEWS  OF  THE  MORAL  LAW. 

conscience,  is  not  duty,  because,  although  good,  nay,  even  a 
higher  species  of  good,  it  does  not  come  into  the  category  of 
duty,  this  being  too  low  for  it.  Here  belongs  the  doctrine  of 
the  so-called  Evangelical  Counsels  (or  the  consilia  ijcrfcctionis), 
which,  to  be  sure,  in  their  consequences,  prove  to  be  very 
unevangelical,  and  even  lead  back,  in  their  own  way,  to  a 
constrained  and  painful  service  of  works.  The  doctrine  holds 
that,  besides  what  belongs  to  common  morality,  there  is  an 
uncommon,  higher  morality  which  God  has  not  commanded, 
but  which  confers  perfection — opera  supcrerogatoria ,  some- 
thing superobligatory.  By  such  oiKva,  many  say  further,  a 
thesaurus  operum  is  filled  up  which  is  under  the  control  of  the 
Church,  and  contains  merits  which  are  transferable  to  others, 
and  so  make  indulgences  possible.  According  to  this,  not  the 
whole  life  and  all  its  powers  are  embraced  by  the  law  of 
duty,  which,  though  unconditional,  yet  is  modified  according 
to  the  individuality ;  but  rather  there  is  one  part  reserved  for 
man  which  he  can  dispose  of  arbitrarily.  If,  now,  with  refer- 
ence to  what  he  is  under  no  obligation  to  do,  he  restricts  or 
gives  up  his  freedom,  i.e.  his  right  of  arbitrary  conduct,  for 
the  sake  of  the  perfection  which  can  be  a  matter  only  of 
advice,  he  acquires  for  himself  a  merit. ■^  To  this  higher, 
optional  excellence  belong  not  so  much  certain  good  works 
recommended  by  the  Church,  such  as  fasting,  alms-giving, 
mortifications  (except  in  so  far  as  they  reach  a  very  unusual 
degree),  as  rather,  particularly,  the  so-called  vows  of  poverty, 
of  chastity,  and  of  obedience,  which  involve  the  renunciation 
of  property,  of  marriage,  and  of  personal  freedom.  Of  course 
it  is  assumed  that  those  who  make  the  sacrifice  of  these  three 
things  do  not  fall  behind  others  in  the  realm  of  common 
duties.  But  this  realm  is  unduly  limited  ;  for  example,  the 
duty  of  faithful  management  of  property  is  swallowed  up  by 

^  Cf.  Bellarmin,  Je  Controversil<i  Jidel  chr.  torn  2,  lib.  ii.  cap.  9  ;  J.  A.  Moliler, 
SymboUk,  ed.  6,  pp.  159,  213  sq.  [Symbolism,  etc.,  urans.  from  the  German 
by  Jas.  B,  Robertson,  Lond.  184.3,  pp.  181,  240  sq.— Te.]  ;  C.  T.  Werner, 
System  der  christlichen  Ethik,  1850-52,  vol.  i.  pp.  368,  408  ;  Martin,  de 
C'onsiliis  quce  vocantur  perfection^,  1850  ;  Julius  Mliller,  Lehre  von  der 
Si'md.e,  vol.  i.  p.  64  sq.  ed.  5  [In  English  :  The  Christian  Doctrine  of  Sin,  trans, 
by  AV.  Urwick  (Clark,  Edin.  1868),  vol.  i.  p.  52.— Tr.]  ;  Schmid,  Sittenlehre, 
p.  441  ;  Rothe,  ed.  1,  vol.  iii.  p.  90  ;  Wuttke,  vol.  i.  §  81  [Christian  Ethics, 
vol.  ii.  §  80.— Te.]. 


THE  CONSILIA  EVAXGELICA.       THE  EXEGETICAL  ARGUMENT.     205 

the  pretended  perfection  which  rejects  the  possession  of 
property  as  being  worthless  for  the  development  of  personal 
morality. 

In  defence  of  this  doctrine  of  the  Consilia  Evangelica,  both 
exegetical  and  intrinsic  reasons  are  adduced.  As  the  founda- 
tion of  the  whole  doctrine  of  the  Evangelical  Counsels,  Luke 
xvii.  1 0  is  given ;  while,  for  the  vows  of  poverty  and  of 
celibacy  in  particular,  Luke  xviii.  22,  Matt.  xix'.  11,  12,  21, 
1  Cor.  ix.  14-17  are  adduced.  Mohler  understands  Luke 
xvii.  1 0  thus :  Christ,  he  says,  calls  it  unprofitable  when  one 
does  not  do  more  than  it  is  his  duty  to  do ;  consequently  the 
Christian  must  do  more  than  is  his  duty.  But  the  passage 
does  not  say  that :  it  says  rather  that  with  respect  to  what- 
ever he  can  do  the  man  ouglit  to  say,  "  What  I  have  done  is 
no  more  than  it  was  my  duty  to  do ;  I  have  therefore  no 
merit,  no  rightful  claim  to  reward.  On  the  contrary,  I  am 
an  unprofitable  servant ;  I  have  brought  to  God  no  profit 
which  He  is  bound  to  requite ; "  just  as  the  master  spoken  of 
in  the  context  owes  the  slave  no  thanks.  The  passage,  there- 
fore, means  this  :  With  reference  to  whatever  of  good  we  have 
done  we  ought  to  say.  We  are  unprofitable  servants ;  we  have 
only  done  what  it  was  our  duty  to  do.  And  this  requires 
that  we  regard  also  the  so-called  good  of  the  Consilia  rather 
as  something  due,  that  is,  as  duty.  We  are  unprofitable  all 
the  more,  since  we  are  all  to  regard  ourselves  as  sinners,  who 
have  rather  to  beg  forgiveness  than  to  demand  a  reward. 
If  the  meaning  were  that,  when  the  common  duties  are  done, 
the  man  remains  still  an  unprofitable  servant,  then,  in  order 
not  to  be  unprofitable,  he  would  be  under  oUigation  to  strive 
after  perfection ;  and  thus  too  out  of  the  counsel  results  duty 
and  command.  Besides,  the  whole  passage  is  directed  against 
Pharisaic  self-righteousness ;  to  this  a  back-door  would  be 
opened,  if  Jesus  meant  to  exhort  us  to  do  anything  more 
than  our  duty,  that  is,  anything  meritorious.  How  would 
the  universal  necessity  of  redemption  consist  with  this  ? 
Christ  means  to  exhort  us  to  humility,  and  through  humility 
to  faith  (vers.  5  and  6).  Finally,  Jesus  does  not  say  that 
any  one  has  done  everything,  but  only  supposes  the  case, 
and  even  in  this  He  declares  that  there  is  no  room  for  merit 
or  self-congratulation. 


206      §  21.  HEFUTATION  OF  ERRONEOUS  VIEWS  OF  THE  MORAL  LAW. 

Ill  Matt.  xix.  21,  where  the  renunciation  of  riches  is 
spoken  of,  Jesus  does  not  cancede  to  the  young  man  that  he 
has  kept  the  whole  law  from  youth  up  ;  for  this  law  forbids 
even  evil  desires.  He  does  not  say,  as  Martin  affirms,  that, 
since  the  young  man  has  fulfilled  the  law,  he  only  needs,  in 
order  to  perfection,  also  to  give  up  his  possessions.  For  Jesus 
regards  him  as  not  yet  righteous  and  pleasing  to  God,  as  not 
yet  a  member  of  the  kingdom  of  God ;  but  He  regards  him 
as  still  standing  outside  of  the  kingdom  of  God,  for  He  says, 
after  the  youth  has  gone  away  sorrowful,  "  How  hardly  shall 
they  that  have  riches  enter  into  the  kingdom  of  God ! " 
Otherwise  how  could  He  call  on  him  to  lay  up  treasure  in 
heaven  and  to  follow  Him  ?  Jesus'  words  rather  are  designed 
to  help  the  young  man  to  a  knowledge  of  himself,  to  make 
him  see  how  much  his  heart  still  clings  to  earthly  treasures. 
If  his  desire  to  attain  to  the  kingdom  of  God  was  earnest  and 
victorious,  he  followed  after  Jesus, — a  service  which  then 
involved  outward  separation  from  his  home, — and  was  able  to 
become  perfect ;  as  we  all  through  Christ  can,  and  should, 
become  perfect  (Matt.  v.  48).  The  requirement  that  he 
should  divest  himself  of  his  outward  possessions,  was  the 
test  whether  his  heart  clung  to  his  wealth  as  the  highest 
good ;  and  to  be  able  at  first  to  stand  this  test  inwardly  was 
for  this  particular  youth  the  condition  of  discipleship. 

When  in  Matt.  xix.  11,  12  those  are  spoken  of  who  for 
the  kingdom  of  heaven's  sake  refrain  from  marriage  (as,  e.g., 
Paul  did  on  account  of  his  work),  and  when  it  is  added,  "  He 
that  is  able  to  receive  it,  let  him  receive  it ;  all  men  cannot 
receive  this  saying,  but  they  to  whom  it  is  given,"  it  is  most 
distinctly  affirmed  that  it  is  not  left  to  man's  mere  option 
whether  he  shall  refrain  from  marriage,  but  that  that  depends 
on  a  special  individual  gift.  He  to  whom  "  it  is  given  "  has  in 
this  gift,  as  in  everything  to  which  he  is  entitled,  a  talent  for 
which  he  is  responsible ;  just  as  he  who  is  personally  fitted 
for  marriage  is  fulfilling  his  vocation  when  he  lives  as  a 
married  man.  In  all  men  should  dwell  the  spirit  of  love, 
which  wholly  devotes  itself  to  the  interests  of  the  kingdom 
of  God,  according  to  the  requirements  of  one's  vocation  and 
individual  characteristics.  Whether  this  unselfish  devotion 
requires    marriage    or    celibacy,    is    to    be    decided    by    that 


SUPEREKOGATOKY  WORKS.       THE  EXEGETICAL  ARGUMENT.        207 

wisdom  of  love  which  must  give  directions  for  the  right  use 
of  freedom,  that  is,  must  seek  the  place  in  which  this  freedom 
can  exert  itself  most  fruitfully. 

Tliese  passages  certainly  teach  that  the  one  universal  and 
absolute  fundamental  duty  of  love  adapts  itself  to  individual 
characteristics  and  circtimstances.  The  same  love  uses  the 
different  individualities  in  wisdom ;  this,  however,  does  not 
open  to  them  a  domain  of  caprice  and  option,  but  rather  each 
individual  is  embraced  by  the  one  law  of  many  members, 
which  requires  for  love  a  rich  and  manifold,  but  not  uniform, 
manifestation.  What  is  dut}^  for  the  individual,  in  view  of 
his  individuality,  others  cannot  decide ;  it  can  also  not  be 
determined  by  any  abstract  rule.  Ultimately  in  every  act 
something  must  be  left  to  the  conscience  of  the  individual, 
but  so  left  that  under  like  circumstances  every  one  would 
have  to  do  the  same  that  is  the  duty  of  the  individual. 
In  1  Cor.  vii.  17,  20,  where  Paul  speaks  of  marriage  and 
celibacy,  he  lays  down  the  general  rule,  "  Let  each  one  abide 
in  his  calling,"  that  is,  in  consideration  of  his  individual 
characteristics  which  decide  concerning  his  calling.  1  Cor. 
ix.  14—17  does  not  at  all  bear  upon  the  matter  in  question. 
For  when  Paul  says  that  it  is  his  privilege  to  live  of  the 
gospel,  but  that  he  refrains  from  doing  so  for  the  gospel's 
sake,  this  does  not  mean  that,  because  he  has  a  claim  on  the 
Christians  to  be  supported  by  them,  and  yet  makes  no  use  of 
it,  therefore  this  is  optional  with  him  in  the  sight  of  God 
also.  Eather  Paul  believed  that,  in  God's  judgment,  he  had 
no  right  to  do  otherwise  than  he  did.  But  the  most  convinc- 
ing confutation  of  this  whole  doctrine  of  Evangelical  Counsels 
is  found  in  Jas.  iv.  17,  cf.  Luke  xii.  47,  "To  him  that  knoweth 
to  do  good  and  doeth  it  not,  to  him  it  is  sin."  Therefore  what 
the  Consilia  Evangelica  advise  is  either  not  good  but  the  con- 
trary, in  which  case  failure  to  do  it  is  duty ;  or  it  is  something 
good,  in  which  case  failure  to  do  it  is  sin,  and  the  performance 
of  it  is  duty.  But  the  positive  side  of  the  confutation  lies 
in  the  fact  that  the  law  is  the  law  of  love,  which  is  the 
apaKe(f)a\aLO)ai<i  of  the  law.  Por  according  to  this  there  can  be 
nothing  good  which  lies  above  it  or  beneath  it.  Love  itself, 
however,  is  what  absolutely  all  men  are  required  to  exercise ; 
it   is   not    merely  the   duty  of    certain    individuals.      Since, 


208      §  21.  REFUTATION  OF  ERRONEOUS  VIEWS  OF  THE  MORAL  LAW. 

therefore,  love  claims  all  the  faculties  for  itself,  there  is  left 
no  place  for  the  Consilia  Evangelica. 

There  are  intrinsic  reasons,  however,  adduced  on  the 
Eoman  Catholic  side  for  the  Consilia  Evangelica.  Mohler 
says :  The  love  which  dwells  in  the  Christian  is  infinitely 
superior  to  the  law,  since  it  is  able  to  discover  more  and 
more  tender  relations  to  God  and  to  the  world,  and  never 
satisfies  itself.  But  this  implies  a  very  low  conception  of  the 
law,  even  as  to  its  positive  contents.  Inasmuch  as  love  com- 
prehends all  the  commandments,  all  of  them  being  fulfilled  in 
love,  how  shall  one  go  to  work  in  order  to  do  anything  beyond 
what  the  law  of  love  requires  ?  Or  shall  we  say  that  love 
itself  is  not  commanded  ?  How  can  one  by  loving  accom- 
plish anything  that  is  superior  to  love  ?  Just  here  it 
becomes  very  evident  how  pregnant  with  evil  it  has  been  for 
the  Eoman  Catholic  doctrine,  that  its  teachers  have  not 
grasped  the  doctrine  of  the  law  and  the  gospel  as  found  in 
the  New  Testament  and  set  forth  by  the  Eeformation.  The 
Consilia  Evangelica  are  an  ethical  monstrosity,  full  of  con- 
tradictions, which  can  be  cleared  up  only  by  a  correct  appre- 
hension of  the  difference,  and  of  the  oneness,  of  law  and 
gospel.  In  the  doctrine  of  the  Evangelical  Counsels  the 
Eoman  Catholic  ethics  tends,  on  one  side,  towards  the 
Evangelical  standpoint.  For  therein  the  feeling  asserts  itself, 
that  the  universality  of  the  moral  law  cannot  be  taken  in  the 
sense  of  the  uniform  sameness  of  the  law  for  all  men,  but  that 
there  must  be  a  place  for  individual  freedom ;  hence  one 
person  may  properly  engage  in  a  worldly  vocation,  while 
another  may  remain  a  monk.  But  the  freedom  which  the 
Consilia  Evangelica.  allow  must  not  be  confounded  with  the 
moral  attitude  which  grows  out  of  personal  peculiarities.  For 
though  these  peculiarities  find  a  sort  of  recognition  in  the 
Consilia,  yet  the  counsels  are  not  regarded  as  duty  for  the 
individual  just  as  he  is. 

Again,  it  cannot  but  be  seen  that  in  these  counsels  the  feel- 
ing asserts  itself,  that  in  general  the  legal  standpoint  cannot 
be  regarded  as  the  highest  one  in  morality.  An  attempt  is 
made,  however,  to  find,  above  the  law,  a  special  region  which 
is  practically  quite  other  than  that  of  the  common  moral  law, 
and  is  of  a  nobler,  or,  as  it  were,  more  heavenly  sort.     But 


THE  LA.W  OF  FKEEDOM.  209 

the  contents  of  the  moral  law  retain  even  under  the  gospel  their 
immutable  holiness ;  and  the  legal  stage  cannot  be  left  behind 
by  dissolving  the  contents  of  the  law,  or  by  making  them  less 
binding  through  the  introduction  of  a  higher  element.  This 
can  be  done  only  by  the  person's  assuming  another  attitude 
than  before,  viz.  the  evangelical  attitude,  towards  the  holy 
and  imperishable  law.  Then  the  law  does  not  merely  stand 
over  against  the  will  in  such  a  way  that,  even  when  the  will 
does  the  required  deeds,  these  are  done  not  from  love,  but  only 
from  impure  motives,  or  at  the  best  only  out  of  regard  for 
the  law.  Eather,  in  love  man's  freedom  and  the  immutable 
imperative  demands  of  morality  become  perfectly  blended. 
'Now  through  an  optical  illusion  it  comes  to  pass  that  the 
person,  instead  of  looking  for  the  defect  in  himself,  i.e.  in  his 
attitude  towards  tlie  law,  looks  for  it  in  the  law  on  its 
objective  side.  Instead  of  giving  its  rightful  place  to  the  all- 
comprehending  law  of  love,  which  is  also  freedom,  he  lets 
another  sort  of  law,  a  merely  advisory  rule  of  conduct,  enter 
in,  which  is  made  subject  to  free  choice,  i.e.  to  pure  option. 
The  truth  is  overlooked,  that  the  genuine  Christian  freedom 
consists  in  one's  being  bound  by  the  Spirit  of  God,  and  must 
not  be  identified  with  option  and  caprice.  The  moral  law  is 
looked  upon  as  something  enslaving,  that  is,  as  opposed  to 
freedom ;  and  it  is  not  seen  that  it  is,  rather,  a  law  in  favour 
of  freedom, — a  law  that  is  seeking  an  embodiment,  and  finds 
it  in  that  most  exquisite  and  free  delight  which  sees  and  loves^ 
in  the  law  of  the  good,  nothing  but  that  which  is  truest  to- 
one's  own  nature.  In  a  word,  in  the  view  under  considera- 
tion, ethical  necessity  and  ethical  freedom,  both  of  which 
demand  of  course  to  be  recognised,  fail  to  become  united  and 
blended,  because  an  incorrect  conception  of  both  prevails. 
The  necessary  and  the  free  are,  rather,  assigned  to  two 
different  classes  of  men.  Freedom  is  reserved  only  for  the 
disciples  of  the  Consilia  Evangclica,  who  pass  for  a  spiritual 
class  morally  higher  than  others,  and  are  thus  led  to  cherish 
the  conceit  of  spiritual  elevation  above  the  law  and  a  false 
notion  of  the  autonomy  of  their  free  will ;  while  the  other 
class  does  not  get  beyond  a  servile,  constrained  attitude 
towards  the  law. 

Note. — The  force  of  these  arguments  is  not  evaded  by  Werner 

0 


210      §  21.  EEFUTATION  OF  EKEONEOUS  VIEWS  OF  THE  MORAL  LAW. 

either  (vol.  i.  pp.  393-407).  He  concedes  that  for  common 
duties,  even  for  duties  of  right,  a  spirit  of  love  must  be  required. 
He  concedes  that  poverty,  obedience  to  superiors,  and  celibacy, 
and  in  general  all  outward  works,  apart  from  a  loving  disposi- 
tion, fail  to  constitute  perfection.  He  even  says  (p.  407)  that 
the  Consilia  Evangclica  are  also  to  be  regarded  as  duty.  But 
if  so,  they  would  cease  to  be  mere  consilia;  and  the  apparent 
concession  is  to  be  explained  by  the  fact  that  he  regards  the 
Consilia  Evangelica  as  duty  only  ibr  those  who  already  stand  in 
these  relations  and  are  bound  to  them  by  vow. 

2.  Something  of  this  Eoman  Catholic  mode  of  conception 
has  penetrated  the  ethics  of  Protestants  also.  This  may  be 
said  of  .A.mmon,  when  he  speaks  of  degrees  of  obligation,  and 
lays  down  a  distinction  between  perfect  and  im'perfcct  duties, 
reckoning  especially  duties  of  right  as  belonging  to  the  first 
class,  and  the  others  as  not  belonging  to  it.  Similarly  Kant 
says  that  the  violation  of  strict  duty,  or  the  duty  of  right, 
involves  guilt,  whereas  that  of  duty  in  the  wider  sense,  or 
such  duty  as  constitutes  virtue,  does  not  involve  guilt,  but 
only  the  absence  of  moral  worth,  while  the  fulfilment  of  them 
involves  merit.  Love,  which  he  elsewhere  sets  aside,  here 
tries  again  to  find  a  place ;  and  this  indicates  a  vague  feeling 
that  there  is  a  higher  moral  stage  than  the  legal  one.  But 
the  way  by  which  Kant  comes  to  it  is  objectionable.  It  is 
incorrect  not  to  regard  love  as  duty,  and  the  neglect  of  it  as 
o-uilt.  To  him  that  knoweth  to  do  good  and  doeth  it  not,  to  him 
it  is  sin  (Jas.  iv.  17).  And  Paul  says, "  Owe  no  man  anything, 
but  to  love  one  another."  Degrees  of  duty,  in  themselves  and 
objectively  considered,  are  out  of  the  question.  For  duty  is 
something  in  its  nature  unconditional  (Eothe,  1st  ed.  §  834)  ; 
but  the  unconditional  has  no  degrees.  It  is  only  in  a  sub- 
jective sense  that  we  can  speak  of  degrees  of  obligation,  in  so 
far  as  there  are  different  degrees  in  the  clearness  of  the  moral 
sense,  or  of  the  consciousness  of  obligation,  as  e.g.  in  the  case 
of  an  oath.  An  oath  does  not  increase  the  obligation  of 
veracity  (this  exists  without  the  oath),  but  it  does  sharpen 
one's  own  consciousness  of  the  obligation.  But  the  same  is 
true  of  all  duties  which  have  an  absolute  character.  Therefore 
neither  is  the  duty  of  rectitude  a  more  perfect  duty  than  the 
duty  of  benevolence,  nor  vice  versa.  It  is  true  that  in  the 
execution  of  anything,  that  which  is  the  foundation  or  neces- 


IMPERFECT  DUTIES.       TERMLSSIBLE  ACTIONS.  211 

saiy  condition  must  precede  the  structure  itself.  The  duty  of 
rectitude  is  the  foundation.  But  the  foundation  and  the 
morality  built  up  on  it  are  hoth  alike  commanded ;  in  the 
proper  benevolent  disposition  which  must  also  be  required  for 
the  duties  of  rectitude,  both  of  them,  indeed,  are  at  once  willed 
and  united.  Amongst  the  manifold  things  which  are  necessary 
to  the  accomplishment  of  the  moral  end  for  which  the  world 
exists,  there  is  a  distinction  which  has  a  logical  and  real  im- 
portance :  That  which  is  means  to  the  end  must  be  chosen  first. 
But  the  obligation  to  choose  it  is  not  therefore  any  greater. 

3.  More  difficult  and  disputed  is  the  question  whether, 
besides  obligatory  things,  there  are  permissible  ^  things  respect- 
ing which  one  can  act  purely  according  to  option — a  view 
taken  by  not  a  few  moralists,  among  them  Chalybaus.  On 
the  one  hand,  it  seems  in  the  highest  degree  objectionable  to 
give  up  to  arbitrary  free  will  a  sphere  which  it  may  seek  to 
fill  up  with  meritorious  deeds,  and  such  as  transcend,  as  it 
were,  moral  obligation.  Upon  the  assumption  that  there  is  a 
sphere  of  being  not  affected  by  duty,  and,  so  far  forth,  beneath 
morality,  there  may  be  built  up  only  too  naturally  the 
assumption  of  something  that  is  above  morality.  If  the  moral 
laM^  covers  everything,  and  if  it  knows  nothing  but  uncondi- 
tional requirements,  it  cannot  grant  permits  to  rove  about 
av6/jico<;  at  pleasure.  On  the  other  hand,  it  does  not  seem  as 
if  it  could  be  demanded  that  every  action  of  a  person  should 
be  regarded  as  duty  ;  e.g.  that  in  walking  I  take  the  first  step 
with  the  right  foot  and  not  with  the  left ;  that  in  eating  I  lay 
hold  of  this  and  not  of  that  article  of  food.  If  everything 
were  subsumed  under  the  category  of  duty,  would  not  one's 
whole  life  be  decomposed  into  atoms,  and,  through  continual 
reflection,  all  ease  and  freedom  of  flow  in  the  moral  life  be 
lost  ?  To  use  Kant's  language,  would  not  the  whole  moral 
world  be  strewn  with  the  traps  of  duty  ?  An  ethics  which  would 
bring  together  everything,  the  smallest  as  well  as  the  greatest, 
under  the  notion  of  unconditional  duty  seems  certain  to  result 

^  Sclileiermacher,  Ueher  das  ErlauUe,  Werke,  vol.  ii.  p.  41S  sq. ;  Hartenstein, 
Grundhegriffe  der  ethischen  Wissenscliaften,  p.  346  sq. ;  Chalybaus,  Philo- 
sophische  Etliik,  i.  §  74 ;  Rotlie,  1st  ed.  vol.  iii.  p.  24  sq. ;  Martensen,  Christian 
Ethics,  §  133  sq. ;  KiJstlin,  Jahrhilcher  fur  deutsche  Theologie,  vol.  xiv.  p. 
464  sq. ;  Wcndt,  Ucbcr  das  sittlich  Erlaubte,  1880. 


212      §  21.  EEFUTATION  OF  ERRONEOUS  VIEWS  OF  THE  MORAL  LAW 

in  over-strictness,  and  to  favour  scrupulousness  and  a  morbid 
development  of  the  conscience.  The  solution  of  these  seeming 
contradictions  will  be  found,  if  we  take  our  start  from  the 
correct  conception  of  moral  action,  as  well  as  of  the  per- 
missible, including  the  so-called  morally  indifferent. 

As  to  moral  action,  we  must  distinguish  between  it  and  a 
factor  of  the  action.  Every  action,  as  a  relative  whole,  is 
subject  to  the  law  of  duty  ;  but  there  is  not  a  special  duty  for 
every  factor  in  such  an  action.  There  are  also  functions  of  a 
physical  or  psychical  kind,  which  constitute  no  action  of  the 
person,  but  are  only  accompanying  motions,  or  such  as, 
according  to  the  character  of  the  organism,  act  a  subservient 
part.  It  is  an  action,  e.g.,  when  I  carry  out  a  resolution  to 
take  recreation  by  walking  in  the  open  air.  This  volition,  now, 
works  on  of  itself  in  every  step,  and  takes  the  organism,  as  it 
is,  without  special  further  reflection,  into  its  service.  The 
case  is  similar  with  the  whole  realm  of  amusement  and  enjoy- 
ment. This  also  is  embraced  by  the  law  of  duty,  but  by  no 
means  so  that  the  free  pleasure  and  movement  must  be 
hampered  by  reflective  and  anxious  legality.  Duty  and  moral 
law  have,  it  is  true,  the  decisive  voice  in  the  resolution  to 
indulge  in  recreation,  sport,  and  enjoyment ;  they  have  like- 
wise the  right  to  demand  that  in  all  this  nothing  impure  shall 
be  admittted.  But  this  is  possible  without  a  legal,  anxious 
watching  of  one's  self.  The  agent  can,  and  should,  attain 
freedom,  not  from  duty  and  law,  but  in  them ;  he  should 
acquire  a  moral  tact,  the  product  of  a  matured  faculty  for 
virtue ;  and  this  tact,  without  any  troublesome  reflection, 
and  by  virtue  of  a  naturally  indwelling  moral  perception,  will 
hit  upon  that  which  is  proper  objectively  and  for  the 
individual. 

Now,  as  to  the  notion  of  permissible,  or  morally  indifferent, 
actions,  here  likewise  we  must  premise  that  moral  or  immoral 
actions  are  out  of  the  question,  until  the  consciousness  of  duty 
or  of  law  is  awakened.  Certainly  the  right  to  the  exercise 
of  one's  freedom  cannot  be  denied  to  man,  even  before  the 
awaking  of  the  moral  consciousness.  In  this  sense,  therefore, 
there  will  indeed  always  be  things  permitted,  because  neither 
commanded  nor  forbidden ;  but  this  does  not  give  us  permis- 
sible moral  actions ;  for  these  are  ante-moral  acts^  which  are 


THE  THEOEY  OF  PERMISSIBLE  ACTIONS.  213 

not  as  yet  subject  to  moral  judgment.  It  is  true,  even  after 
the  moral  sense  is  aroused,  it  may  happen  that  the  agent  sees 
before  him  various  possible  things,  respecting  which  it  is  not 
at  once  clear  to  him  whether  all  of  them  are  possible  con- 
sistently with  morality,  or  whether  one  or  another  among 
them  is  so.  When,  now,  one  must  nevertheless  take  action, 
it  may  be  said :  The  one  thing  is,  in  a  moral  respect,  as 
possible  as  the  other,  i.e.  they  are  all  equally  permitted.  But 
it  is  plain  that  here,  too,  there  is  lacking  an  element  essential 
to  the  notion  of  a  moral  action,  viz.  the  consciousness  of  the 
power  of  the  law  to  take  in  also  this  other  action.  [One  does 
not  even  know  in  this  case  whether  the  law  commands, 
forbids,  or  only  allows  it. — Ed.]  But  now,  are  there  not 
morally  indifferent  actions  ?  That  could  be  the  fact  only  in 
case  the  moral  law  itself  laid  down  various  moral,  and  equally 
excellent,  possibilities,  according  to  the  principle  that  difiereut 
means  or  ways  may  lead  to  the  same  end.  But  what  is 
indifferent  in  one  respect  will  yet  not  be  so  in  another, 
because  every  definite  act  of  a  person  will  have  its  peculiar 
relations  and  effects  in  other  directions.  Accordingly  nothing 
but  want  of  a  clear  perception  of  these  relations  can  be  the 
reason  why  in  this  case  a  variety  of  morally  indifferent  actions 
is  sometimes  assumed.  Absolutely  morally  indifferent  nothing 
can  be ;  because  the  moral  law  is  authorized  to  embrace  and 
sanction  everything. 

§  22.   Oneness  of  the  Moral  Law,  and  Conflict  of  Duties. 

However  manifold  the  moral  law  may  be,  in  reference  to  the 
actions  and  works  which  it  requires,  it  cannot  stand  in 
opposition  to  itself;  for  we  must  ascribe  to  it  perfect 
oneness  in  and  with  itself.  Hence  there  can  be  no 
objective  conflict  of  duties. 

Literature. — Eothe,  1st  ed.  vol.  iii.  §  854,  856,  p.  63  sqq.  Von 
der  Goltz,  Ueher  die  Ursachen  der  Collision  von  Pflichten,  in  the 
DeutscJi-Evangelischen  Blatter  for  June  1879.  Frank,  System  der 
christlichen  Sittlichkeit,  §  22,  p.  393  sq.     Cf.  the  literature,  §  20. 

1.  The  oneness  of  the  moral  law  has,  in  the  first  place,  a 
negative  meaning.      It  is  not  discordant  in  itself,  and  cannot 


214       §  22.    ONENESS  OF  THE  LAW,  AND  CONFLICT  OF  DUTIES. 

contradict  itself.  For  if  the  moral  law  is  characterized  by- 
necessity  and  absoluteness,  there  cannot  be  opposite  things 
which  are  both  at  once  absolutely  obligatory,  because  in  that 
case  the  one  would  nullify  the  other.  But  the  more  emphatic 
meaning  of  the  unity  of  the  moral  law  is  the  positive  one : 
It  constitutes  a  compact  unity  or  totality,  not  merely  in  the 
formal  sense  that  it  all  has  the  same  source  and  authority, 
but  in  the  sense  that  it  is  one  in  itself,  amidst  all  its  manifold- 
ness,  which  comes  from  the  one  duty  being  divided  into  a 
multitude  of  actions  and  operations.  By  virtue  of  its  one- 
ness the  whole  is  present  in  its  parts,  and  affirms  itself  in 
them  ;  the  consequence  of  which  is,  that  no  part  of  the  whole 
duty  can  be  willed  without  the  whole  being  implicitly  willed 
also,  and  likewise  that  the  moral  law,  even  when  violated 
only  in  one  part,  is  yet  even  in  this  part  violated  as  a  whole. 
This  is  the  sentiment  which  runs  through  the  whole  Epistle 
of  James  (ii.  10,  iv.  12).  Inasmuch  now  as  this  one  law  at 
the  same  time  embraces  and  dominates  everything,  even 
nature  included,  whose  place  is  fixed  by  the  laAv,  how  can 
there  be  place  in  it  for  self-contradiction  ? 

The  ^proposition,  that  there  can  be  a  conflict  of  duties  only 
in  appearance,  Protestant  moralists  can,  of  course,  more 
strictly  maintain  than  the  Eoman  Catholic  can ;  although 
Eoman  Catholic  moralists  also,  like  Schreiber  and  the  most 
evangelical  of  them,  Hirscher,^  would  also  like  to  have  a  part 
in  defending  it.  Not  only  does  the  Eoman  Catholic  Church 
admit  the  Scotist  doctrine,  according  to  which  there  may  be 
one  kind  of  morality  for  man  and  another  for  God's  action  ; 
but  also  within  the  world  of  human  beings  a  twofold  species 
of  morality  is  said  to  be  constituted  by  the  Consilia 
Evangelica  —  that  is,  beside  the  common  morality,  the 
morality  of  perfection.  Although  modern  writers,  like 
Martin,  Werner,  and  others,  try  to  call  this  a  misunder- 
standing, and  to  reduce  the  difference  of  kind  to  a  difference 
of  degree,  this  is  not  satisfactory.  Logically  the  Consilium 
Evangelimim  would  have  rather  to  be  made  a  universal  duty  ; 
because  it  must  be  duty  to  overcome  every  defect  which 
makes  one  come  short  of  perfection.  Again,  it  is  the 
characteristic    of   things    distinguished   only   in  degree,  that 

1  Lc.  ii.  199. 


OBJECTIONS  TO  THE  ONENESS  OF  THE  MOEAL  LAW.         215 

the  lower  are  included  and  preserved  in  the  higher,  but  not 
excluded  by  them.  But  how  shall  one  exercise  himself 
ethically  with  reference  to  possessions,  freedom,  and  marriage, 
when  he  sustains  towards  these  things  the  purely  negative 
attitude  which  the  Consilia  Evangelica  recommend  ?  We 
must  therefore  insist  that  these  consilia  involve  a  relative 
depreciation  of  important  departments  of  moral  life,  while 
yet  they  extol  this  depreciation  as  perfection.  A  part  of 
morality,  viz.  religious  life,  is  here  brought  into  collision 
with  the  rest  of  morality,  and  tries  to  live  at  its  expense. 
That  purely  negative  attitude  could  be  called  moral  only  in 
case  the  Manichsean  view  of  the  good  things  of  creation 
were  correct ;  but  in  that  case  again  it  would  be  a  universal 
duty  to  renounce  them. 

2.  Against  this  notion  of  the  solidarity  of  the  moral  law, 
or  of  duty,  doubts  and  difiiculties  are  raised,  derived  in 
part  from  the  nature  of  morality  itself,  and  especially  from 
the  antithesis  between  the  general  and  the  particular.  How 
is  a  conflict  of  duties  avoidable,  ask  Daub  and  Marheinecke, 
when  yet,  on  the  one  hand,  man,  limited  in  time  and  space, 
can  at  each  moment  choose  only  a  single  thing ;  whereas,  on 
the  other  hand,  the  law,  this  ideal  organism,  comprehends  all 
good,  and,  moreover,  everything  is  absolutely  eternally  binding, 
and  does  not  first  become  duty  in  time  ?  This  difficulty 
applies  not  only  to  individuals,  but  also  to  communities. 
For  example,  the  Church  should  grow  intensively ;  but  it 
should  grow  also  extensively,  through  missions.  The  indi- 
vidual should  work  for  others,  but  he  should  also  constantly 
grow  inwardly  by  means  of  self-culture.  Both  prayer  and 
labour  are  duties.  How  much  time  may  each  lay  claim  to  ? 
What  shall  be  done  in  all  these  cases  ?  Every  discliarge  of 
duty  is  in  a  certain  respect  a  solution  of  the  problem  of  a 
conflict  of  duties,  because  many  things  require  to  be  accom- 
plished at  once.  But  how  is  this  solution  to  be  found  ? 
Schleiermacher  intensifies  the  problem  by  the  further  observa- 
tion, that  moral  action,  in  each  of  its  three  forms,  namely,  of 
action  which  portrays,  action  which  purifies,  and  action  which 
propagates,  presents  an  infinite  work  to  be  done,  so  that  if  the 
accomplishing  of  the  work  is  begun  with  one  of  them,  the 
others  will  never  be  reached. 


216       §  22.    ONENESS  OF  THE  LAW,  AND  CONFLICT  OF  DUTIES. 

One  might  here  attempt  to  evade  the  difficulty  by  saying 
that  obligation  is  out  of  the  question  so  long  as  one  has  no 
hiowlcdge  of  that  to  which  the  law  obligates  him ;  that  this 
knowledge,  however,  is  a  growing  knowledge  which  he  does 
not  have  from  the  outset.  This  evasion  is  not  valid ;  for 
knowledge  goes  farther  than  the  mere  discharge  of  each  duty 
as  it  arises.  It  goes  before  the  action,  and  early  embraces  the 
whole  man,  and  a  multitude  of  duties  which  cannot  all 
actually  pass  at  once  into  actions,  although  they  are  yet 
obligatory.  Daub  and  Marheinecke  try  to  distinguish  between 
obligation  and  duty,  making  the  former  a  latent  thing  embrac- 
ing also  that  which  will  not  need  to  be  realized  till  the  future, 
while  duty  is  made  to  be  that  which  points  to  something  to 
be  done  now.  But  this  does  not  sufficiently  guard  the  unity  of 
the  moral  law.  A  latent  obligation  would  be  for  the  moment 
no  obligation ;  and  yet  it  exhibits  a  certain  vitality  in  the 
very  fact  that  there  is  a  moral  knowledge  concerning  it ;  this 
knowledge  is  a  knowledge  of  duty.  Moreover,  it  would 
imply  mutability  in  the  law,  if  what  before  was  not  duty,  but 
only  obligatory,  should  become  duty  by  means  of  time. 
Eather  we  must  say :  If  there  is  a  consciousness  of  obligation, 
it  must  be  seen  that  the  thing  which  it  requires  can  also  be 
undertaken. 

The  correct  solution  is  given  by  Schleiermacher :  The 
unity  of  the  moral  law  is  secured  by  the  very  fact  that  when 
I  will  to  do  a  single  thing,  I  can  include  in  my  volition  the 
sum-total  of  morality,  by  undertaking  what  I  have  to  do  in 
the  manner  prescribed  by  wisdom.  Every  individual  thing  is 
to  be  chosen  as  a  part  of  the  whole ;  and,  therefore,  with  this 
choice  of  the  whole,  which  is  implied  in  the  moral  choice  of 
the  individual  thing  in  question,  there  begins  already  the 
accomplishment  of  that  which  takes  its  turn  later,  as  a  thing 
to  be  done,  though  it  presupposes  the  previous  thing  as  its 
foundation.  Moral  wisdom  discerns  in  the  moral  law  also 
the  appropriate,  logical  order  of  succession  contained  in  it,  so 
that  there  cannot  be  several  incompatible  duties  contending 
to  be  done  at  the  same  moment.  Thus,  righteousness  logically 
precedes  the  positive  manifestation  of  love,  being  necessarily 
presupposed  in  it.  He  who  is  in  debt  should  first  think 
about  getting  out  of  debt,  and  must  not  deprive  himself  of 


EVEN  SIN  OCCASIONS  NO  EEAL  CONFLICT  OF  DUTIES.       21 7 

the  possibility  of  doing  so  by  liberality ;  for  this  would 
rather  be  a  taking  away  from  others :  giving  would  be  a 
wrongful  show  of  right  doing.  Schleiermacher  also  observes 
further,  that  in  all  moral  actions  all  the  three  kinds  are 
involved — that  which  portrays,  that  which  purifies,  and  that 
which  propagates,  so  that  though  one  may  preponderate,  yet 
the  essential  unity  and  connection  is  preserved. 

Those,  now,  who  affirm  the  reality  of  an  objective  conflict 
of  duties  urge  that  through  sin  an  objective  derangement  has 
come  in,  and  that  the  world  which  was  made  for  harmony  is 
put  out  of  joint.^  Through  sin,  it  is  said,  discord  enters  into 
the  objects  of  moral  choice,  and  therefore  into  the  purposes  of 
action.  Thus  arise  a  multitude  of  objective  conflicts  of  duties, 
among  which  especially  deserve  to  be  named  the  duties  which 
one  owes  to  himself,  and  towards  God  and  men, — the  duty  of 
labouring  for  the  kingdom  of  God,  and  the  duty  of  caring  for 
one's  self.  Furthermore,  there  are  the  ethical  communities, 
each  of  which  can,  through  sin,  come  into  dissension  both 
with  itself  and  with  the  others.  Frank,  now,  unhesitatingly 
assumes  that,  from  the  derangement  caused  by  sin,  a  con- 
dition of  things  results  in  which  real  duties  are  opposed  to 
each  other  and  yet  contend  to  be  done  at  the  same  moment. 
The  ground  of  the  conflicts,  he  thinks,  is  not  to  be  found 
merely  in  a  subjective  lack  of  moral  wisdom ;  consequently 
wider  knowledge  would  not  resolve  them.  It  not  seldom 
occurs,  he  says,  that  the  discharge  of  one  duty  violates 
another  duty,  which,  being  a  real  one,  also  expresses  the 
divine  will.  He  would,  to  be  sure,  accord  to  the  Christian 
(p.  416)  the  hope  of  solving  the  problem  of  the  conflict  of 
duties,  in  so  far  as  he  is  in  fellowship  with  Christ,  in  whom, 
as  regards  principles,  a  complete  solution  is  presented.  But,  on 
the  other  hand,  he  regards  it  (pp.  417,  418)  as  possible  that, 
even  where  the  impulse  comes  to  a  correct  decision,  according 
to  the  relations  to  the  highest  good  and  to  absolute  duty,  it 
may  thereby  in  another  direction  come  "  to  an  apparent  or 
real "  violation  of  duty.  He  even  not  indistinctly  recom- 
mends (pp.  422,  423)  that,  in  certain  exigencies,  when  there 
is  a  conflict  between  the  duty  of  love  and  that  of  veracity,  an 

1  Frank,  System  der  christlichen  Sittlichhelt,  first  half,  1884,  §  22,  pp.  393, 
406-423. 


218       §  22.    ONENESS  OF  THE  LAW,  AND  CONFLICT  OF  DUTIES. 

untruth  should  be  told,  e.g.  to  a  passionate;  or  insane  man,  who 
may  be  threatening  the  life  of  another ;  and  he  says  that  it 
cannot  be  regarded  as  wrong,  when  the  would-be  murderer  is 
looking  for  the  other  man's  hiding-place,  intentionally  to  put 
him  on  a  false  track,  instead  of  merely  preserving  silence 
towards  him. 

The  matter  is  still  more  complicated  in  other  cases,  as 
when  something  has  been  neglected  at  an  earlier  point  of  time 
on  which  something  at  a  later  point  depends.  The  deficiency 
caused  by  the  former  guilt  has,  as  its  consequence,  that  now, 
at  one  and  the  same  moment  several  requirements  are  made 
to  which  one's  capacity  is  unequal,  and  of  which  each  one 
excludes  tlie  other,  inasmuch  as  they  cannot  all  be  fulfilled 
together ;  while  yet  the  fulfilment  of  all  of  them  is  duty, 
being  the  divine  will.  So,  for  example,  it  is  in  communities. 
If,  in  the  State,  poverty  and  immorality  constitute  a  mis- 
chievous circle,  each  being  continually  the  cause  of  the 
other,  the  question  arises  :  Which  task  is  first  to  be  attempted, 
the  removal  of  the  poverty  or  the  removal  of  the  immorality  ? 
But  the  solution  of  the  contradiction  is  here  plainly  possible ; 
for  by  means  of  the  division  of  labour  both  tasks  can  be 
undertaken  together.  In  the  individual  life,  however,  the 
beginning  must  be  made  with  the  moral  cognitions,  and  the 
aim  must  be  to  produce  virtuousness.  Frank  must  him- 
self concede  that  for  Christ  there  was  no  objective  conflict  of 
duties.  This  involves  the  admission  that  in  the  world,  in 
which  Christ  as  well  as  others  had  to  live  and  work,  sin 
causes  no  such  derangement  that  an  objective  conflict  of 
duties,  all  obligatory  at  the  same  moment,  can  necessarily 
result  from  it.  The  derangement  or  confusion  of  moral 
relations  caused  by  sin  has  indeed  an  effect  on  the  course 
which  the  moral  process  takes ;  but  the  realm  of  duty  itself 
does  not  therefore  come  into  contradiction  with  itself.  It 
asserts  itself  in  reality,  in  spite  of  the  confusion,  by  the  fact 
that  it  indicates  the  possible  remedy  and  the  way  to  it.  A 
correct  moral  perception  finds  the  order  in  which  can  be 
accomplished  the  fulfilment  of  duties  which  seem  to  demand 
simultaneous  attention. 

3.  Casuistry,  by  dissolving  the  unity  of  the  moral  law  into 
independent  duties,  has  found  a  wide  field  for  its  acumen.      It 


CASUISTRY,  219 

sets  the  duties  in  opposition  to  one  another,  either  in  order  to 
seek  a  decision  and  at  the  same  time  to  revel  in  a  dialectical 
exercise,  or  in  order  to  lay  the  foundation  of  a  moral  doubt 
which  shall  have  to  be  settled  especially  by  the  father  con- 
fessors. On  the  one  hand  it  is  said,  "  Thou  shalt  not  kill ;  " 
on  the  other,  in  war  the  command  to  kill  is  valid.  A  promise 
is  made  to  do  something  which  it  is  sinful  to  do  ;  but  while 
one  must  not  commit  sin,  one  must  also  not  violate  a  promise. 
In  such  a  case  there  seems  even  to  be  no  possibility  of  finding 
a  way  out,  consistently  with  morality.  For  there  seems  here 
to  be  sin  in  the  very  failure  to  sin,  because  this  failure  is  a 
breach  of  promise ;  while  also  it  would  be  sinful  to  keep  the 
promise.  Or  conversely,  the  commission  of  sin  involves  the 
doing  of  good,  viz.  the  keeping  of  a  promise.  In  like  manner 
the  so-called  lie  of  necessity  says :  Thou  shalt  sometimes  lie 
for  love's  sake.  In  this  case  one  duty  is  always  selected  as 
an  abstract  thing,  and  is  set  up  as  an  individual  duty  absolutely 
in  opposition  to  others  ;  whereas  it  should  be  conceived  of  as 
a  member  of  the  whole,  so  that  in  the  volition  the  whole 
must  be  willed,  and  not  its  opposite.  Except  for  this  error 
nothing  which  is  right  could  be  forbidden,  and  nothing  which 
involves  a  violation  of  another  duty  could  really  assume  the 
appearance  of  an  obligatory  command.  The  solution  of  such 
concrete  cases  of  apparent  conflict  is  possible  only  when  we 
start  with  the  recognition  of  the  organic  unity  of  all  moral 
action,  and  of  the  intrinsic  relation  of  the  members  of  the 
moral  world  to  one  another.  The  basis  for  the  solution  of 
such  cases  lies,  therefore,  in  the  recognition  of  the  relations  of 
the  moral  spheres  to  one  another. 

Note. — Other  cases  of  alleged  objective  conflicts  of  duty  which 
are  adduced  would  have  to  be  accurately  stated  before  they  can 
be  solved.  The  persecution  of  apostles  and  confessors  was,  as 
Paul  after  his  conversion  painfully  saw,  a  grave  sin.  On  the 
other  hand,  the  persecutors  may  think  themselves  to  be  doing 
God  service ;  accordingly,  since  it  is  duty  to  do  good  when  one 
knows  it,  and  in  doing  so  one  must  follow  his  own  conviction, 
even  though  erroneous,  sin  seems  to  be  involved  in  the  omission 
of  sin,  i.e.  of  the  persecution.  This  case  of  conflict  is  solved  by 
the  consideration  that  what  is  not  of  faith  is  sin.  A  persecutor 
of  Christians  does  not  stand  in  the  faith ;  whether  he  persecutes 
or  fails  to  persecute,  he  stands  in  sin,  that  is,  in  opposition 


220       §  22.    ONENESS  OF  THE  LAW,  AND  CONFLICT  OF  DUTIES. 

to  duty ;  and  so  here  too  an  objective  conflict  of  duties  is 
excluded,^ 

On  the  other  hand,  suhjcdive  conflicts  of  duties  are  indeed  not 
to  be  denied.  It  is  very  possible  that  a  man  through  lack  of 
wisdom,  or,  in  general,  of  moral  force,  may  sometimes  stand 
still  in  perplexity,  and  not  know  which  of  several  moral  duties 
he  is  first  to  lay  hold  of.  Here  belongs  the  celebrated  case  of 
the  plank  which  two  shipwrecked  persons  grasp,  while  it  is  able 
to  bear  only  one.  Which  of  the  two  shall  give  way  ?  This 
cannot  be  told,  because  the  data  for  a  moral  decision  are  as 
yet  too  vague  and  abstract.  In  real  life  there  will  be  always 
disclosed  a  ditieience  in  the  claims,  because  there  are  no  two 
persons  entirely  alike  and  alike  situated ;  two  such  would 
rather  be  one,  and  so  the  conHict  of  duties  would  disappear.  If 
the  concrete  data  are  given,  the  moral  faculty,  in  the  form  of 
wisdom,  can  come  to  a  decision.  Eothe  in  this  connection  calls 
attention  to  the  difference  in  individuals,  it  the  individual  is 
heroic,  he  will,  without  further  consideration,  aim  to  save  the 
other.  If  he  is  governed  more  by  the  principle  of  caution,  it 
will  be  allowable  to  deliberate  which  of  the  two  shall  die. 
Only  it  would  be  bad  if  one  should  stick  to  the  plank  for  the 
reason  that  he  regards  himself  as  the  better,  or  as  more  import- 
ant for  the  kingdom  of  God.  If  the  case  is  supposed  that  the 
claims  of  both  are  entirely  equal,  and  no  difference  between 
them  is  discoverable,  so  that  neither  of  them  morally  would 
have  the  right  to  give  way  to  the  other  or  to  remain,  then  they 
are  brought  into  a  predicament  in  which  both  must  perish  or 
await  death,  in  order  not  to  act  immorally  in  one  direction  or 
the  other.  By  this  putting  of  the  case  they  are  both  with 
mathematical  necessity  destined  to  die  ;  and  that  is  a  smaller 
misfortune  than  that  either  should  intentionally  kill  himself  or 
the  other.  The  persons  do  not  need,  even  in  such  a  case,  to  be 
morally  unproductive.  The  Christian  in  such  a  position,  await- 
ing death,  would  still  be  able  in  prayer  to  realize  his  fellowship 
with  God. 

We  still  insist,  after  all,  that  tJici^e  can  he  no  such  objectively 
7iccesso.ry  conflict  of  duties  as  could  not  he  solved  hy  wisdom.  Even 
sin  cannot  affect  this  conclusion.  For  that  would  imply  that 
evil  may  gain  such  a  power  that  the  good  could  be  accomplished 
only  by  means  of  evil,  and  that,  too,  forbidden  evil.  Kather, 
the  only  effect  of  evil  is,  that  the  healing  of  the  moral  faculties, 
together  with  everything  which  makes  that  healing  possible 
and  actual,  now  enters  into  the  circle  of  the  duties  ;  to  seek  this 
cure  must  be  the  first  duty,  because  it  is  the  prerequisite  of  the 
discharge  of  every  other  moral  duty.     For  example,  in  the  case 

^  Cf.  what  is  said  by  the  author  lower  down  on  the  so-called  erring  conscience. 


§  23.    DUTY  AND  RIGHT.  221 

of  a  drunkard,  the  first  thing  required  is  nothing  else  than  a 
state  of  sobriety ;  this  furnishes  the  possibility  of  his  coming  to 
the  consciousness  of  his  general  condition,  and  thereby  to  a  real 
conversion.  If  there  is  a  lack  of  moral  power,  what  is  done  in 
spite  of  the  lack  is  indeed  not  a  matter  of  indifference  ;  but  it 
is  not  possible  for  him  to  take  an  actual  part  in  the  general 
moral  work  (Matt.  vii.  17,  18). 


§  23.  Duty  and  Right} 

From  the  notion  of  the  moral  law,  which  may  also  be  called 
GocVs  objective  rigid  (t2Qt^'p),  there  arises,  first,  that  of  duty, 
because  the  law  involves  an  unconditional  Ouglit  which 
concerns  all  rational  beings  (§19  sqq.).  But  from  duty, 
which,  as  being  something  morally,  and  not  physically, 
necessary,  is  addressed  to  freedom,  and  presupposes 
freedom,  there  results  also  for  man  a  right  and  a  realm 
of  rights.  For  out  of  the  unconditional  obligatory  Ought 
there  results,  first  of  all,  the  primordial  right,  or  funda- 
mental right,  of  man  to  do  his  duty, — the  right  to  be  a 
moral  being.  There  is  no  power  which  has  the  right  to 
prevent  this.  For  a  right  which  should  oppose  this 
universal  duty  would  undermine  the  very  foundation  of 
right  itself.  All  actual  human  rights  are  derived  from 
the  law  {i.e.  the  objective  right)  through  the  medium  of 
obligation,  and  exist  as  objects  of  duty.  They  constitute 
the  ]possihility  of  the  accomjjlishmcnt  of  duty,  and  this  is 
the  absolute  ground  on  which  they  rest. 

1.  Duty  and  right  in  genercd,  in  relation  to  the  objective 
law,  or  God. — The  divine  right  is  identical  with  the  divine 
law,  and  has  therefore  been  already  treated  of  in  the  foregoing. 
The  divine  law  can  be  called  divine  right  because,  oxi 
account  of  its  intrinsic  excellence,  it  has  the  right  to  make 
unconditional  requirements,  in  order  to  put  men  under  obli- 
gation to  produce  that  order  of  human  life  which  corresponds 
to  it.  But  the  point  now  is  to  discern  how  a  right  and  rights 
also  accrue  to  man,  and  that  out  of  his  duty  and  his  duties. 

'  [Cf.  Trendelenburg,  Naturrecht,  §  45 ;  vid,  the  literature,  §  33a. — Ed.] 


222  §  -23.    DUTY  AND  EIGHT. 

True,  the  first  thing  empirically  is  not  tlie  consciousness  of 
duty  and  law,  but  the  power  of  the  will  to  exercise  itself  in 
various  ways ;  and  the  created  being  is  entitled  or  authorized 
to  exercise  this  inborn  power.  But  this  right  is  an  ante- 
moral  one,  and  has  nothing  to  do  with  moral  right  until  the 
consciousness  of  a  law  springs  up  ;  it  therefore  does  not  itself 
as  yet  stand  fast  as  having  the  character  of  necessity.  The 
moral  law,  moreover,  cannot  be  derived  from  it.  If  we  start 
from  right  and  rights,  instead  of  from  duty  and  duties,  we 
cannot  reach  a  right  which  is  worthy  of  the  name.  Right, 
when  it  is  not  based  on  duty,  is  identical  with  the  permissible 
or  the  morally  indeterminate ;  and  nothing  is  more  natural 
than  that  this  option  (that  is,  spurious  freedom),  once  admitted, 
should  seek  to  extend  its  limits  more  and  more,  and  when 
the  law  makes  its  appearance,  to  hem  it  in  as  if  it  were  an 
enemy.  But  in  this  way  human  right  itself  and  the  totality 
of  human  rights  lose  just  their  security.  If  right  and  the 
assertion  of  it  are  not  deepened  into  duty,  it  has  no  absolute 
necessity ;  a  person  may  behave  as  he  pleases  about  it,  and 
may  treat  national  and  public  rights  as  private  affairs ;  and 
Avhere  this  becomes  general  it  leads  to  the  ruin  of  the  whole, 
and  to  the  ruin  of  the  rights  of  the  individual.  But  over 
against  others  also,  right  is  in  this  case  not  secured.  If 
my  right  is  not  founded  in  an  objective  law  which  becomes 
duty,  it  is  itself  not  objective,  my  right  does  not  obligate 
another  person  to  recognise  it,  it  is  only  identical  with  my 
power.  And  since  the  same  is  true  of  others  with  reference 
to  me,  there  occur  collisions  in  which  the  stronger  prevails 
But  the  right  of  the  stronger  is  as  such  no  right  at  all.  Eight 
is  the  revelation  of  an  absolute  idea,  and  therefore  something 
objective. 

But  duty  also  cannot  stand  as  something  fixed,  unless  it  is 
allowed  to  constitute  the  foundation,  that  is,  to  occupy  the 
first  place,  and  not  merely  a  secondary  one,  dependent  on 
option.  It  might  indeed  be  thought  that  even  if  we  make 
right,  or  tlie  rights  of  the  moral  agent,  and  not  duties,  our 
starting-point,  we  may  yet  attain  to  real  duty  and  a  common 
objective  right  by  means  of  convention  and  agreement,  and 
that  thus  marriage  and  the  family  relation,  religious  and  poli- 
tical communities,  may  be  built  upon  conventional  agreements. 


DUTY  AND  EIGHT  IN  HUJIAN  EELATIONS.  223 

Bat  without  tlie  recognition  of  the  moral  duty  of  faithfulness 
to  treaty  arrangements  there  can  be  no  treaty  rights  estab- 
lished ;  and  so  again  the  priority  of  duty  before  subjective 
right  is  clear.  Duty  has  no  such  ignoble  origin  that  it 
must  owe  its  existence  to  the  option  of  moral  agents.  It 
is  duty  rather  which  first  makes  man  actually  rational ;  it  is 
therefore  to  be  recognised  as  the  necessary  foundation,  and 
from  it  fixed  objective  right  is  to  be  derived.  The  person 
is  to  defend  his  personal  rights  as  the  organ  of  the  moral 
idea,  and  for  the  sake  of  that  idea,  not  from  mere  regard  to 
self. 

2.  Duty  and  right  in  the  relation  of  man  to  man.  —  As 
related  to  God,  there  is  at  first  a  duty,  but  no  right,  such  as 
would  make  us  co-ordinate  with  God.  From  the  fundamental 
relation  of  obligation  to  God  is  also  derived  man's  first  right, 
namely,  the  right  to  fulfil  duty.  On  the  other  hand,  men 
are  co-ordinate  with  one  another ;  and  in  the  relation  of  man 
to  man  the  obverse  of  my  duty  to  another  is  the  right  of  the 
latter ;  and  the  obverse  of  my  right  is  the  duty  of  the  other 
to  recognise  it.  Unless  this  were  the  duty  of  the  other  man, 
then  there  would  not  be  really  any  right  on  my  part.  That 
my  right  is  the  other's  duty,  the  other's  right  my  duty,  makes 
right  and  duty  correlative.  The  two  thus  stand  conditioning 
one  another ;  if  one  falls,  the  other  falls  also.  But  they  can 
be  correlates  only  in  case  they  both  spring  from  an  objective 
law  standing  above  them,  which  cherishes  the  true  interests 
of  all,  being  just  in  itself,  and  loving  all  alike — a  law  which 
both  obligates  all  equally,  and  endows  all  with  rights.  Hence, 
in  order  to  establish  the  reality  of  a  system  of  human  rights, 
that  is,  the  relation  of  reciprocal  rights  and  duties,  we  must 
go  back  to  an  objective  right  independent  of  the  human 
agent, — to  one  which  is  founded  ultimately  in  God  Himself, 
nay,  which  is  God  Himself.  This  law  is  in  itself  the  objec- 
tive aboriginal  right,  that  is,  God's  righteous  order ;  and  this 
becomes  law  and  duty  for  the  world.  By  the  side  of  God's 
aboriginal  right,  or  His  righteousness,  stands  power,  as  the 
arm  of  righteousness,  by  means  of  which,  against  violations  of 
His  unconditional  law,  He  maintains  the  law's  honour,  which 
is  at  the  same  time  His  own  honour. 

Duty  is  therefore  for  man  the  first  thing.      God  has  the 


224  §  23.    DUTY  AND  RIGHT. 

unconditional  o^ight  to  impose  obligation,  to  require  that  His 
will  shall  prevail.  God  has  created  the  world  not  only  from 
love,  but  for  holy  love ;  hence  the  world  is  under  obligation 
to  do  what  is  morally  good ;  and  just  herein  is  also  laid  the 
foundation-stone  of  a  human  right,  an  objective  and  absolute 
right,  which  does  not  depend  on  treaty,  or  custom,  or  positive 
legislative  stipulations,  but  stands  as  impregnable  as  a  duty. 
That  is,  mans  primordial  right,  the  true  fundamental  right, 
ivhich  results  from  his  duty,  is  the  right  to  he  a  moral  being. 
This  is  a  great  good,  the  moral  honour,  incomparably  higher 
than  the  honour  considered  in  the  First  Division/  Two 
elements  are  involved  in  this — a  purely  negative  and  a  posi- 
tive one.  No  human  being  can  rightly  be  treated  as  if  he 
were  not  designed  for  that  which  is  absolutely  worthy,  and 
this  for  him.  This,  hov/ever,  involves,  positively,  the  right 
of  this  moral  honour  or  moral  destination  to  assert  itself — 
one's  right  to  exercise  activity,  but  also  one's  right  to  receive 
from  others.  The  latter  is  the  prerequisite  of  the  former, 
being  that  by  which  the  real  moral  personality  is  77iade  possible. 
Thus  we  have  a  firm  foundation  of  right  for  the  individuah 
It  does  not  depend  on  the  option  of  the  human  agent  to 
surrender  the  right  to  be  a  moral  being  and  the  possibility 
of  realizing  his  moral  destination.  This  right  is  not  at  his 
disposal,  because  this  right  is  also  a  right  which  the  law  has 
over  him ;  in  other  words,  it  is  his  duty ;  and  in  this  con- 
sciousness this  right  is  to  be  maintained. 

Note. — From  the  idea  of  objective  divine  right  there  results 
for  the  moral  agent  the  sense  of  duty,  which  again  on  its  part 
lays  the  foundation  for  the  recognition  of  the  mutual  rights  of 
persons.  When  this  idea  springs  up  in  the  consciousness,  then 
tlie  State  takes  its  rise  ;  and  everything  spoken  of  in  §  17,  all 
the  natural  excellences  of  individuals  and  all  the  associations 
which  spring  up  naturally,  being  now  placed  under  the  aspect 
of  objective  right  and  law,  attain  a  higher  position.  But  they 
reach  this  higher  form  only  through  the  moral  process  itself, 
and  through  what  it  has  to  deal  with.  Hence  this  cannot  be 
discussed  till  we  come  to  the  Third  Division.  Having  considered 
the  doctrine  of  the  objective  law  (§20  sqq.),  we  come  now  to 
the— 

1  Vid.  above,  p.  190.     Cf.  in  general,  §  18. 


THE  doctrinf:  of  conscience.  225 

SECOND  SECTION. 

THE  DOCTIJINE  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

§  24. 

Conscience,  which  is  the  one  pole  of  our  moral  nature,  §  19, 
is,  considered  in  its  origin,  the  voice  of  God,  while  at 
the  same  time  it  is  also  man's  own  knowledge,  the  voice 
of  innate  reason.  As  to  its  form,  conscience  claims  the 
power  of  making  all  moral  good  unconditionally 
obligatory.  As  to  its  contents,  it  includes  the  know- 
ledge of  the  distinction  between  good  and  evil  in 
general,  while  in  addition  to  this  it  also  includes — ■ 
in  proportion  to  its  degree  of  development  —  tlie 
special  knowledge  of  what  actions  are  good  or  bad. 
Conscience  as  legislative  is  called  antecedent ;  as  a  motive 
power  and  as  a  witness  of  particular  actions  it  is  called 
concomitant ;  finally,  in  its  character  of  critic  or  judge  of 
actions  that  are  past  it  is  said  to  be  subsequent.  But 
in  all  its  temporal  forms  of  manifestation,  conscience, 
although  the  representative  of  the  ethically  necessary, 
is  an  evidence  of  human  freedom  ;  it  addresses  itself 
to  freedom,  presupposes  it  as  a  faculty  already  existent, 
and  serves  to  bring  it  to  realization. 

LiTERATUKE. — Stiiudlin,  Gcseliichte  cler  Lehre  vom  Gcivissen, 
1824.  Crusius,  Lchrhueh  der  chr.  Sittenlehre  (treats  more 
particularly  of  the  motive  power  of  conscience).  De  Wette, 
Vorlesungen  ilher  Sittenlehre,  1823,  i.  2,  p.  315  sq.  Christliche 
Sittenlehre,  i.  p.  90.  Daub,  Morcd,  i.  pp.  75,  377.  Eothe, 
i.  262,  §  147  ;  2nd  ed.  §  177,  note  3.  Passavant,  Das 
Gnuissen,  2nd  ed.  1857.  Schenkel,  article  Gcwissen  in 
Herzog's  Beal-Eneyklo2Jddie,  and  his  Bogmatik  aus  dem  Stand- 
'punhtc  des  Geioissens,  1856,  i.  135  sq.  Glider,  Erorterung 
'iiber  die  Lehre  vom  Gewissen,  nach  der  Schrift,  in  Studien  unci 
Kritikcn,  1857,  2.  Schlottraann,  Ueher  den  Begriff  des 
Gewissens.  Beutsche  Zeitschrift,  1857,  Nr.  15  sq.  Heman, 
Aphorismen  IXher  das  Gewissen.  Jaltrhilcher  fur  deutselic  Th.  xi. 
483  sq.     Kostlin,  I.e.  p.  181.     R  Hoffmann,  Bic   Lehre   vom 


226  §  24.    THE  DOCTPJNE  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

Gewissen,  1866.  Delitzsch,  System  dcr  hillischen  PsycJwlogic, 
§  4.  Beck,  Umriss  dcr  MMischen  Seelenlehrc,  71  sq.  Gass,  Die 
Lehre  vom  Getuisscn,  1869,  with  an  appendix  on  die  Synderesis. 
Eitschl,  Veher  das  Gewissen,  1876.  Martin  Kahler,  Die  schrift- 
gemdsse  Lelire  vom  Gewissen  in  Hirer  Bedeutiuig  fur  christliches 
Lchen  unci  Lehrcn,  1864,  and  the  larger  work  by  the  same 
author,  Das  Geivissen,  Part  i.  1878.  (These  are  elaborate  gram- 
matical investigations.)  Cremer,  Biblico-thcologiccd  Lexicon, 
art.  (jijvoiha.  J.  J.  Hoppe,  Das  Geivissen,  1875  (a  psychological 
discussion).  [Ulrici,  Gott  unci  der  Menscli,2i\di  ed.  ii.  p.  366  sq. 
Sommer,  Geivissen  und  moderne  Cidtur,  1884. — Ed.] 

1.  Conscience  is  one  of  the  most  important  topics  in  the 
whole  of  ethics,  and  even  in  the  whole  of  theology,  especially 
evangelical  theology.  The  characteristic  of  the  evangelical 
standpoint  with  reference  to  the  appropriation  of  Christianity 
is,  that  instead  of  following  mere  subjective  opinions  or  the 
current  of  dominant  human  authorities,  it  both  demands  and 
promises  that  Christian  truth  be  vindicated  to  the  conscience 
itself,  and  is  therefore  in  a  position  to  hold  up  personal 
assurance  of  faith  as  an  attainable  goal.  There  is  even  a 
still  plainer  connection  than  this  between  conscience  and  the 
central  truth  in  the  evangelical  doctrine  of  salvation.  The 
announcement  of  justification  as  an  act  of  divine  grace,  or 
the  free  forgiveness  of  siu,  addresses  itself  to  aroused  and 
awakened  consciences,  for  such  alone  are  truly  capable  of 
arriving  through  repentance  at  that  faith  which  is  able  to 
appreciate  at  its  true  worth  the  prevenient  grace  of  God,  and 
to  appropriate  the  offered  boon.  Moreover,  as  conscience 
when  it  is  angry  and  accusing  incites  us,  if  it  be  properly 
guided,  to  seek  Him  who  is  the  divine  atonement  for  sin,  so 
it  becomes,  if  this  atonement  be  accepted  in  sincere  penitence 
and  faith,  the  abode  of  the  peace  of  God.  Yea,  a  good 
conscience  now  becomes  the  very  soul  of  sanctification.  This 
is  the  reason  why  the  writings  of  the  Eeformers,  Luther's 
especially  and  Calvin's,  are  so  full  of  passages  about  con- 
science and  its  different  functions,  although  it  is  true  that 
they  did  not  furnish  a  complete  doctrine  of  conscience.  Such 
a  doctrine,  indeed,  we  do  not  possess  even  yet.  The  post- 
Eeformation  theology,  like  that  of  the  Middle  Ages,  treated 
conscience  in  a  one-sided  intellectual  way — as  a  Byllorjismns 
yraeticus.     Even   such   as   admit   it   to   be   an   original  and 


BIBLICAL  DOCTRINE  OF  CONSCIENCE. 


227 


luiderived  faculty,  and  refuse  to  ]jase  it  upon  empiricism  or 
reflection,  are  at  variance  among  themselves  on  several  points. 
They  disagree  as  to  whether  it  is  most  allied  to  knowledge, 
will,  or  feeling ;  and  further,  to  say  nothing  about  their  differ- 
— -  "-    f^  fLo  rplation  which   conscience  holds   to  religion. 


226  §  24.    THE  DOCITJNE  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

Gewissen,  1866.  Delitzsch,  System  clcr  hihlischcn  Psychologic, 
§  4  Beck,  Umriss  dcr  hihliscjien  Seelenlclirc,  71  sq.  Gass,  Die 
Lelire  vom  Gewissen,  1869,  with  an  appendix  on  die  Synderesis. 
Eitschl,  Ueher  das  Gewissen,  1876.  Martin  Kahler,  Die  schrift- 
gemdsse  Lehrc  vom  Gewissen  in  Hirer  Bedeutung  fur  christliches 
Lchen  mid  Lehren.  1864-    nn/l  +k^  i 


BIBLICAL  DOCTPJNE  OF  CONSCIENCE.  227 

luiderived  faculty,  and  refuse  to  base  it  upon  empiricism  or 
reflection,  are  at  variance  among  themselves  on  several  points. 
They  disagree  as  to  whether  it  is  most  allied  to  knowledge, 
will,  or  feeling ;  and  further,  to  say  nothing  about  their  differ- 
ences as  to  the  relation  which  conscience  holds  to  religion, 
they  are  not  at  one  as  to  whether  it  merely  takes  cognizance 
of  past  acts,  and  has  therefore  only  critical  or  judicial  functions 
to  discharge,  or  whether  it  is  legislative  as  well.  Under  these 
circumstances  Rotlie  finds  the  problem  so  difficult,  that  he 
abandons  the  idea  of  a  doctrine  of  conscience  altogether. 

2.  Biblical  doctrine  of  conscience.  —  In  the  Old  Testament 
the  word  conscience  does  not  occur,  but  its  functions  are 
alluded  to  in  a  variety  of  ways,  as  for  instance  in  the  case 
of  Adam  after  his  sin,  of  Cain  both  before  and  after  his, 
and  of  the  brethren  of  Joseph  when  they  were  seized  with 
alarm  in  his  presence  (cf.  further,  Ps.  vi.  2,  xxxii.  1—5, 
xxxviii.  2—11,  li.  19;  1  Sam,  xxiv.  11;  2  Sara.  xxiv.  10; 
Job  xxvii.  6).  It  is  certainly  true  that  no  special  word 
for  conscience  is  to  be  found  in  the  Old  Testament ;  never- 
theless, not  merely  in  the  Old  Testament,  but  also  in  the 
iSTew,  the  heart  is  regarded  as  the  focus  of  the  spiritual  life, 
and  accordingly  the  functions  of  conscience  are  ascribed  to 
it.  We  read  of  David's  heart  smiting  him  ('^3'?)  (2  Sam. 
xxiv.  10),  and  of  a  broken  heart,  that  is,  a  condemning  con- 
science (cf.  1  John  iii.  19,  KapSia  KarayivcoaKovcra).  The 
word  avveiZi](TL'i,  having  come  into  general  use  in  Greek 
philosophy  especially  through  the  influence  of  the  Stoics, 
occurs  in  the  Book  of  Wisdom  (xvii.  11),  and  is  frecjuently 
employed  in  the  New  Testament  by  Paul  and  Peter.  The 
four  Gospels,  it  is  true,  contain  no  passage  in  which  Christ 
makes  use  of  the  word.  But  too  much  stress  must  not  be 
laid  upon  this,  nor  ought  we  to  conclude,  with  Kahler,  that 
Christ  did  not  recognise  conscience  as  a  fact.  It  is  erroneous 
to  hold  that  Christ  simply  demands  faith  in  His  authority, 
and  does  not  presuppose  in  man  a  knowledge  of  his  own  to 
which  He  appeals.^  Were  we  to  take  such  a  view,  we  should 
have  to  ignore  passages  like  John  i,  4,  v.  38,  viii.  32,  and 
to  put  a  forced  interpretation  upon  others,  such  as  Matt, 
vi.  22  ff.,  Luke  xi.  34,  which  speak  of  the  inward  eye  of 
'  Kahler's  book  On  the  Conscience,  1878,  p.  218  sq. 


228  §  21.    THE  DOCTKINE  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

man.  Kiililer  is  also  of  opinion  that  in  the  Old  Testament 
the  entire  moral  consciousness  of  man  is  identified  M-itli  lii.s 
knowledge  of  the  revealed  law,  or  of  the  authority  of  the 
divine  legislation.  But  although  positive  commands  and 
external  authority  have  more  importance  attached  to  them 
in  the  Old  Testament  than  in  the  New,  yet  this  fact  does 
not  completely  describe  the  attitude  of  the  Old  Testament. 
In  Deuteronomy,  for  example,  the  law  is  spoken  of  as  being 
near,  not  the  mouth  only,  but  also  the  heart ;  while  the  Psalms, 
too,  are  full  of  inward  delight  and  joy  in  the  law.^  The 
revealed  law,  moreover,  did  not  remain  a  mere  external 
authority,  but  awakened  in  man  an  increasing  personal 
knowledge  of  morality,  based  on  the  original  constitution 
of  his  nature. 

In  Eom.  ii.  14ftl  Paul  speaks  at  some  length  of  the  con- 
science. Here,  as  in  most  cases  throughout  the  New  Testa- 
ment, reference  is  made  to  conscience  in  its  critical  or  judicial 
aspect,  and  consequently  to  the  relation  of  the  subject  to  a 
moral  standard,  whatever  the  origin  of  the  latter  may  be. 
Thus  conscience  is  spoken  of  as  Ijeaiing  witness  that  one 
tells  the  truth  (Piom.  ix.  1,  2  ;  2  Cor.  i.  12).  As  judicial  it 
is  either  a  pure,  good  conscience  (1  Pet.  iii.  16  and  21  ; 
2  Tim.  i.  3  ;  1  Tim.  iii.  9  ;  Heb.  xiii.  18  ;  Acts  xxiii.  1, 
xxiv.  16),  or  an  evil  conscience  (Heb.  x.  22).  In  the  latter 
case  it  is  called  a  defiled  or  wounded  conscience  (1  Cor. 
viii.  7  and  12),  or  a  seared  conscience,  to  designate  the 
torturing  sense  of  guilt  (1  Tim.  iv.  2  ;  Heb.  ix.  9).  Never- 
theless the  functions  of  conscience  are  not  limited  by  the 
New  Testament  to  criticism  or  judgment,  but  are  also  declared 
to  be  legislative,  as  when  Paul  speaks  of  the  law  which  is 
written  in  the  heart,  as  well  as  when  he  says  that  the 
Gentiles  are  a  law  unto  themselves.  Conscience  is  some- 
times conceived  of  as  the  perception  of  the  voice  of  God, 
and  not  merely  as  one's  own  consciousness  or  the  expres- 
sion of  one's  own  judgment— this  is  seen  even  in  Gen. 
iv.  G  f.  Further,  in  1  Pet,  ii.  19,  a-vveiBrja-a  6eov  may  either 
indicate  knowledge  of  God  as  imposing  commands  and  obliga- 

'  Kiihlei-  holds  that  the  discoveiy  and  development  of  conscience,  as  a  distinct 
faculty,  are  to  be  found  in  the  heathen  world  alone,  and  that  this  did  not  take 
place  iu  Judaism  until  after  its  contact  with  heathendom. 


§  24a.    DIFFERENT  COXCEPTIONS  OF  CONSCIENCE.  229 

tions,  or  it  may  be  the  gcnitivus  aid  oris.  Similarly  by  the 
A,o709  Oeov  in  man,  spoken  of  in  John  v.  38  (cf.  i.  4),  con- 
science must  be  nnderstood,  while  "  the  law  written  in  the 
lieart "  (liom.  ii.  14f.)  refers  us  to  a  higher  authority  and 
to  the  divine  origin  of  conscience  which  points  to  the  tribunal 
of  God.  At  the  same  time  conscience  is  regarded  in  the 
Xcw  Testament  as  one's  own  knowledge,  and  even  as  a  species 
of  self-legislation.  Man — it  is  said — is  drawn  by  nature, 
by  the  vov<i,  to  what  is  objectively  rational,  and  so  to  the 
things  contained  in  the  law.  And  the  v6/xo<i  tou  vo6<i  is 
identified  with  the  vcfio^  Oeov  (Eom.  vii.  23  and  25). 

Further,  the  influence  of  history  and  education  upon  con- 
science is  fully  recognised.  An  increase  in  moral  perception 
and  wisdom  is  demanded  in  general  (Heb.  v.  14  ;  Eom. 
xii.  2),  so  that  the  vov'i  as  Sidvoca  (the  understanding,  which 
brings  everything  under  its  clear,  analytic  light)  has  its  due 
place  assigned  it.  In  like  manner  the  tendency  and  effect 
of  the  course  of  revelation  is  to  unveil  the  law  with  ever 
increasing  clearness,  and  at  the  same  time  in  harmony  with 
man's  own  moral  perceptions.  Further,  these  htavoiat, 
SLaXoyiafioi,  are  undoubtedly  subject  to  error.  And  finally, 
it  is  also  recognised  in  the  New  Testament  that  individuality 
enters  into  the  formation  of  conscience  (1  Cor.  x.  29). 

§  24rt.    (Continuation.)  Thctic  {Positive)  Doctrine  of  Conscience. 

Conscience  is  not  to  be  identified  with  religious  capacity 
nor  witli  the  moral  consciousness  in  general ;  it  is  a 
knowledge  of  moral  good,  and  is  not  primarily  an 
impulse  or  a  mere  feeling.  It  is  moral  consciousness 
characterized  by  originality  and  immediateness,  and 
allied  with  a  certainty  that  is  not  merely  subjective> 
but  both  subjective  and  objective  at  once. 

1.  Schenkel  confuses  conscience  with  religious  capacity. 
But  we  have  already  (§  12.  1,  2)  treated  of  the  difference 
between  religion,  in  which  dependence  and  receptivity  are  the 
leading  characteristics,  and  morality,  in  which  the  very 
opposite  is  the  case.  Conscience  is  frequently  regarded  as 
moral  imjmhc,  and  assigned  therefore  to  the  will.       According 


230  §  24a.    POSITIVE  DOCTPJNE  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

to  Eeinhard/  conscience  is  the  inclination  to  have  one's  actions 
determined  by  the  thouglit  of  the  Deity.  Crusius  calls  it  the 
indindus  rcligiosus.  According  to  Eothe,"  it  is  the  divine 
activity  in  man  under  the  form  of  impulse,  operating  therefore 
through  sensible  perception,  and  so  bound  up  with  bodily 
sensation.  This  impulse  is  followed  by  cognition.  Kahler'^ 
holds  the  same  view.  But  since  impulse  is  tlie  initial  form  of 
all  volition,  this  would  mean  that  the  mere  fact  that  the  sub- 
ject wills  anything  shows  it  to  be  morally  good.  And  in  that 
case  morality  would  have  no  objective  validity,  since  there  are 
other  than  moral  impulses  in  man.  Further,  in  order  that  an 
impulse  may  be  termed  intellectual,  and  still  more,  moral,  it 
must  have  an  appropriate  object,  and  hence  the  moral  must 
be  mentally  present  somehow,  even  if  l)ut  vaguely,  as  the 
object  of  the  impulse.  And  this  is  only  possible  by  means  of 
the  intelligence,  in  some  one  of  the  forms  which  it  can 
assume. 

Others,  like  De  Wette,*  relegate  conscience  to  the  sphere  of 
feeling,  from  which  no  doubt  it  derives  its  liveliness  and 
immediateness  as  well  as  its  personal  character.  Only  the 
proviso  must  be  made,  that  moral  feeling  must  not  be  taken 
as  mere  self-perception  on  the  i^art  of  the  empirical  subject. 
Eather  is  it  the  feeling  of  moral  worth,  the  feeling  of  the 
ideal  beauty  and  sanctity  of  moral  good,  combined  with  the 
perception  of  its  relation  to  the  ego,  of  its  value  for  the 
empirical  ego ;  and  thus  we  have  here  the  germ  of  objective 
moral  cognition.  Feeling  as  such  lacks  clearness,  constancy, 
precision  ;  and  so  the  function  of  cognition  must  step  forward 
on  its  own  account.  In  addition  to  this,  there  is  a  germ  of 
volition  in  feeling,  no  less  than  of  cognition,  and  consequently, 
as  we  have  already  seen,  moral  feeling  must  be  divided  into 
two  com]3onent  elements,  the  one  intellectual,  or  moral  sense, 
the  other  volitional,  or  moral  im2mlse.  When  this  division 
is  made,  conscience  belongs  to  the  intellectual  side  of  moral 
feeling,  and  appears  in  the  first  place  as  moral  sense.  This 
of  course  is  not  conscience  fully  developed  ;  since,  however,  it 
is  no  longer  so  immediately  interwoven  with  feeling,  but  is 

'  Christl  Moral,  5tli  ed.  i.  262. 

*  I.  265  sq.  1st  ed.     In  the  new  edition  l.e  avoids  the  word  as  ambiguous. 

3  P.  26.  "  Christliche  SiUenlehre,  i.  90. 


CONSCIENCE  AND  MOEAL  CONSCIOUSNESS.        231 

directed  to  an  ideal  object,   good  in  itself,  it   is  the   actual 
beginning  of  conscience. 

Conscience,  moreover,  is  not  to  be  identified  with  moral 
consciousness  in  general.  Xot  every  form  of  moral  conscious- 
ness or  of  moral  belief  deserves  to  be  called  conscience. 
Language  itself  connects  conscience  [^(Jcioisscii]  with  certainty 
[Gcwisslicit],  and  certainty  means  something  else  than  merely 
liolding  particular  opinions  or  echoing  moral  ideas  that  are  not 
really  our  own.  If  the  certainty  possessed  by  conscience  is 
real  and  not  merely  imaginary,  then  it  relates  to  something 
objective,  to  a  truth  independent  of  the  subject,  and  is  there- 
fore at  once  objective  and  subjective,  since  conscience  is  in 
direct  contact  with  its  object.  By  means  of  this  contact  there 
is  implanted  in  the  mind  and  imparted  to  it  an  immediate 
consciousness  of  tlie  evidence  and  truth  of  the  moral.  Hence 
it  is  that  Luther,  with  his  fine  linguistic  sense,  has  also  spoken 
of  faith  and  the  assurance  of  faith  as  the  Christian  conscience, 
in  order  to  indicate  that  the  immediate  certainty  of  faith  is 
not  merely  of  a  subjective,  but  of  a  subjective-objective  kind. 
The  word  couscience  itself  {Gewisseii]  also  implies  knowledge 
\_Wisscn'\.  The  prefix  Gc,  which  in  the  case  of  substantives 
expresses  association  [e.g.  Berg,  Gebirgc — Wasscr,  Gcwdsser), 
must  not  be  taken,  as  Leo  does,  to  mean  that  the  moral 
verdict  of  society  is  the  conscience  of  the  individual,  for  this 
would  turn  the  moral  knowledge  possessed  by  man  as  an 
individual,  and  its  certainty,  into  mere  dependence  on 
authority.  On  the  contrary,  it  seems  to  indicate  the  experience 
which  man  has  after  he  has  committed  some — it  may  be 
secret— deed,  that  there  is  One  present  with  him  who  is 
cognizant  of  his  act.  One  whom  he  cannot  escape,  who  sets 
Himself  over  against  him  as  an  enemy,  and  accuses  him ;  an 
unseen  witness  who  is  not  an  empirical  agent  like  himself, 
but  who  both  comes  forward  as  an  accuser  against  him,  and 
also  impends  over  him  as  a  judge,  and  passes  sentence  upon 
him.  It  cannot  be  an  accidental  circumstance  that  the  word 
for  conscience  in  a  large  number  of  languages  expresses 
this  "  knowing  together  "  or  "  knowing  along  with."  Thus 
avveihrjai,^,  conscientia,  conscience  (French  and  English), 
saimvittighcd  in  Danish.  This  sense  of  a  witness  to  our 
actions  makes  itself  felt  most  of  all,  and  conscience  shows  its 


232  §  2t«.    POSITIVE  DOCTi;iNE  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

energy  most  powerfully,  in  that  mysterious  act  of  tlie  inner 
tribunal,  when,  after  a  sinful  deed  has  been  done,  our  moral 
unworthiness  is  suddenly  disclosed  to  us  as  with  lightning 
speed  and  clearness,  when  as  in  a  moment  the  accusation  goes 
forth  against  a  guilt-laden  "  Thoii,"  and  our  sense  of  guilt  tells 
us  that  this  "  Thou  "  means  ourselves,  and  makes  us  feel  that 
we  are  standing  at  a  judgment-bar. 

But  although  it  is  from  this  wonderful  function  that  con- 
science has  derived  its  name  in  many  languages,  and  although 
it  is  after  the  deed  has  been  committed  that  conscience  makes 
its  voice  heard  most  distinctly,  yet  we  must  not  conclude  that 
the  originality  and  immediateness  of  conscience — the  qualities 
wliich  distinguish  it  from  moral  consciousness  generally — 
refer  only  to  past  actions  and  their  value  ;  that  is  to  say,  we 
must  not  infer  that  conscience  is  only  subsequent.  It  could 
not  discharge  the  functions  of  an  immaculate  witness,  accuser, 
and  judge,  if  there  was  not  inherent  in  it  a  sense  of  the  dis- 
tinction between  good  and  evil ;  consequently  it  must  possess 
a  certain  degree  of  self-legislative  power.  Were  it  not  so,  we 
would  have  to  look  elsewhere  for  a  special  faculty  of  self- 
legislation.  It  is  also  evident  that  the  functions  of  legislation 
and  judgment  must  belong  to  one  and  the  same  conscience, 
from  the  fact  that  so  far  as  our  consciousness  of  morality  as 
such  is  concerned,  it  is  relatively  indifferent  wliether  the  act 
to  which  it  refers  be  past,  present,  or  future.  If  there  is  an 
immediate  and  original  consciousness  of  moral  good,  in  other 
words,  a  conscience,  then  the  declarations  of  conscience, 
whether  they  take  the  form  of  demand,  warning,  or  judgment, 
remain  the  same  for  all  time ;  they  are  declarations  regarding 
something  that  is  eternal  and  emlraces  all  time.  If  we  regard 
conscience  as  being  indeed  the  source  of  moral  knowledge,  but 
only  in  its  form  as  consequent,  then  moral  consciousness  does 
not  arise  until  the  act  has  been  done.  But  this  would  mean 
that  the  act  took  place  unaccompanied  by  any  moral  con- 
sciousness whatever,  and  therefore  that  it  is  morally  worthless. 
And  in  that  case  the  act  could  beget  neither  the  feeling 
of  responsibility  nor  of  guilt ;  at  the  most  it  would  be  felt 
only  to  be  injurious  and  discordant. 

The  Imowledge  given  in  conscience  is  accordingly  distin- 
guished from  other  forms  of  consciousness,  and  even  of  moral 


ORIGIN  OF  COKSCIENCE.  233 

consciousness,  by  tlie  fact  tliat  it  does  not  depend  merely  on 
external  prevailing  tenets  or  authorities,  nor  on  reflection  or 
logical  inferences  alone,  but  bears  the  stamp  of  immediateness 
and  creative  originality.  Of  course  this  knowledge  varies  in 
clearness  and  richness,  as  well  as  in  form,  at  different  stagee 
of  progress.  Conscience  is  an  assured  subjective  knowledge  of 
the  objective  validity  and  truth  of  that  which  in  itself  is 
good.  Hence  it  is  not  to  be  wondered  at  that  every  depart- 
ment of  life  should  seek  to  appropriate  this  word  to  itself ; 
thus  we  read  of  a  logical,  critical,  ai'sthetic  and  political  con- 
science. But  that  conscience  to  which  our  science  has  the 
first  claim,  is  distinguished  from  all  other  knowledge  by  its 
contents,  viz.  the  good,  the  holy,  Fas  as  opposed  to  Nefas,  not 
merely  what  is  useful  or  becoming  (honestum)  or  harmonious 
(koKov).  This,  the  contents  of  conscience,  inasmuch  as  it 
holds  good  for  reason  universally,  and  is  absolutely  necessary, 
concerns  the  inmost  nature,  the  essential  part  of  man. 

2.  A  still  wider  difference  of  opinion  exists  as  to  tlie  origin 
of  conscience. 

(a)  Some  derive  it  wholly  from  external  influences,  from 
the  surrounding  moral  atmosphere  and  prevailing  custom, 
in  a  word,  from  education  in  its  widest  sense.  In  support  of 
this  position,  they  appeal  to  the  manifold  contradictions 
existing  in  the  moral  ideas  of  nations,  contradictions  which  go 
to  such  an  extent  that  m.en  are  found  making  it  a  matter  of 
conscience  not  to  omit  practices  which  are  actually  sinful  (e.g. 
the  sacrifice  of  children,  burning  of  widows,  etc.).  It  must  be 
admitted  that  the  customs  which  prevail  within  the  circle  of  a 
nation's  life  exercise  an  extraordinary  power  over  individuals, 
and  also  that  sin  has  caused  an  enormous  confusion  in  moral 
ideas.  But  missionary  efforts  among  the  heathen  prove  every 
day  that  these  influences  can  be  overcome,  and  this  would  be 
impossible  were  it  not  for  the  fact  that  an  appeal  can  be  made 
from  perverted  moral  ideas  to  a  better,  indestructible  moral 
sense,  a  true  conscience,  which  lives  underneath  all  these 
worthless  accumulations.  Tliose  false  notions  can  be  separated 
from  conscience  just  because  nothing  that  is  false,  but  only 
that  which  is  true,  can  be  really  and  indissolubly  allied  with 
the  rational  nature  of  man.  Thus  the  fact  just  alluded  to  is 
sufficient  to  show  that  conscience  cannot  be  derived  from  the 


234  §  2I«.    POSITIVE  DOCTRINE  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

customs  prevalent  in  a  community.  The  same  conclusion 
also  appears  when  we  consider  that,  according  to  this  view, 
there  would  be  no  such  thing  as  real  moral  knowledge  at  all, 
and  that  man  therefore  would  will  the  good,  not  because  it  is 
good,  but  merely  as  something  handed  down  to  him,  something 
foreign  to  his  own  nature.  And  this  would  deny  the  original 
moral  determination  of  man  altogether.  What  this  theory 
calls  conscience  is  only  something  which  may  be  transferred 
to  others  by  means  of  education,  etc.,  and  is  therefore  not 
conscience  at  all,  but  merely  moral  opinion,  a  number  of 
ideas  with  regard  to  moral  action  that  at  some  particular  time 
hold  sway  within  the  community. 

Accordingly,  when  Jesuitism  seeks  to  implant  in  man  a 
foreign  conscience,  in  the  shape  of  the  moral  opinions  of  a 
father  confessor,  or  when  there  is  voluntarily  assigned  to  a 
fallible  man  the  power  of  issuing  decisions — -with  reference 
both  to  matters  of  faith  and  of  morals — that  are  binding 
upon  the  conscience,  then  an  injury  is  done  to  the  divine 
constitution  of  human  nature.  A  similar  verdict  also  must  be 
passed  upon  every  attempt  to  make  the  Church  the  ultimate 
source  of  moral  knowledge.  The  authority  of  the  Church  has 
been  put  forward  in  opijosition  to  that  subjectivism  which 
frequently  disguises  itself  in  the  garb  of  conscience.  But  the 
moral  ideas  which  prevail  in  the  Church  arise  also  in  part  from 
fallible  men.  Having  attained  a  ruling  position  in  the  wide 
circle  of  the  Church,  they  assume  a  semblance  of  objectivity ; 
iu  truth,  however,  they  are  of  no  more  than  subjective 
importance  in  so  far  as  they  come  into  collision  with  objective 
morality.  On  this  account  also,  to  appeal  to  the  Church  as 
the  power  which  fashions  conscience,  and  is  authorized  so  to 
do,  is  merely  to  displace  07ic  form  of  suhfctivism  hj  another, 
for  to  bring  conscience  under  the  so-called  divine  authority  of 
the  Church  can  be  nothing  but  a  subjective,  arbitrary  act. 
Xor  can  conscience  be  produced  by  means  of  a  merely  external 
revelation.  Every  external  revelation  which  seeks  to  impose 
moral  obligations  must  presuppose  some  moral  knowledge  to 
l)egin  with,  upon  which  it  can  lay  hold  in  order  to  be  under- 
stood, and  upon  which  it  can  base  its  claim  to  be  received  by 
man,  in  distinction  from  other  external  influences.  For 
otherwise   man  would  fall  passively  and  blindly  under  any 


CONSCIENCE  NOT  BASED  UPON  SELF-LEGISLATION.         235 

power  whatever.  Even  in  filial  obedience,  although  the  child 
cannot  recognise  the  moral  necessity  of  what  is  commanded 
him,  he  must  at  least  know  iliis — that  obedience  to  his 
parents  is  a  duty.  Hence  man  must  possess  a  knowledge  of 
his  own  with  regard  to  the  good  ;  and  by  this  knowledge 
alone  is  a  foothold  given  to  external  revelations,  and  a  basis 
afforded  for  the  operation  of  those  means  by  which  our  moral 
intelligence  is  cultivated. 

(li)  Now,  while  it  is  thus  clear  that  it  is  througli  his  own 
consciousness  that  man  knows  and  posits  the  good,  yet,  on  the 
other  hand,  we  must  not  regard  self-legislation  on  the  part  of 
man  as  constituting  by  itself  the  ultimate  basis  of  moral 
knowledge  and  of  conscience.  We  must  not  assert,  with 
Delitzsch,  that  the  law,  as  it  appears  in  the  Torah,  is  engraved 
on  the  human  heart.  It  is  erroneous  to  suppose  that  all 
moral  ideas  are  innate  in  man  in  their  complete  shape,  and 
therefore  that  in  this  respect  there  is  no  real  distinction 
between  the  divine  creation  and  legislation.  All  experience 
speaks  to  the  contrary,  and  especially  the  confusion  that  is 
found  in  mankind  with  regard  to  moral  ideas.  Should  it  be 
maintained,  again,  that  moral  ideas  are  not  innate,  but  are 
the  products  of  reason  and  arrived  at  through  reflection, 
then  this  would  be  at  variance  with  the  immediateness  and 
originality,  as  well  as  tlie  involuntary  necessity  which 
characterize  the  uninvited  verdicts  of  conscience.  Conscience 
is  indeed  a  human  faculty,  but  its  acts  do  not  depend  upon 
the  subjective  will  of  the  empirical  human  being ;  it  is  rather 
a  power  over  man.  It  is  not  man  who  possesses  conscience, 
so  much  as  conscience  that  possesses  man.  The  autonomy 
enjoyed  by  man  is  only  secondary,  not  absolute  ;  he  cannot 
put  the  stamp  of  good  or  evil  upon  anything  at  his  own 
pleasure.  The  primary  fact  is,  that  human  reason  has  been 
brought  into  existence  and  constituted  in  a  definite  way. 
Eeason  is  given  to  itself  as  reason,  it  is  not  the  author  of  its 
own  nature.    And  this  points  us  to  the  ultimate  creative  cause. 

(c)  A  third  view  is  that  conscience  is  GocVs  voice.  If  this 
were  taken  as  a  full  account  of  the  matter,  then  it  would  be 
impossible  to  see  how  we  could  have  a  moral  knowledge  of 
our  own  with  regard  to  the  good-in-itself.  Had  we  not  in 
our  own  rational  nature  a  faculty  of  moral  perception,  we 


236  §  24a.    POSITIVE  DOCTEINE  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

could  never  know  that  these  inward  utterances  of  God  were 
good  in  themselves.  Nevertheless  we  must  recognise  a 
certain  truth  in  the  description  of  conscience  as  the  voice  of 
God,  although  Delitzsch^  denies  this,  on  the  ground  that  God 
does  not  hold  intercourse  with  the  sinful  as  He  does  with  the 
innocent.  For  at  all  events  God  is  the  creator  of  reason  ; 
and  further,  He  has  not — as  Deism  maintains — withdrawn 
Himself  after  the  creation,  hut  continues  to  act  as  a  present, 
eflicient  cause,  even  in  the  manifestations  of  reason.  Now,  if 
it  is  through  God  alone  that  we  have  at  every  moment  a 
knowledge  of  the  good,  if  we  see  light  in  His  light  (although 
Ave  may  not  he  directly  conscious  of  the  fact), — then  it  is 
evidently  wrong  to  deny  that  conscience  is  the  voice  or  word 
of  God.  In  addition  to  this,  we  are  aware  that  the  voice  of 
conscience  impels  us  with  a  kind  of  sacred  necessity,  that  in 
it  God  is  making  a  claim  upon  us,  and  the  Divine  Spirit  con- 
straining us  by  His  appeals. 

((/)  The  three  views  which  we  have  stated  must  therefore 
be  taken  together  :  (1)  that  conscience  is  God's  voice  ;  (2) 
that  it  is  also  the  voice  of  our  own  inmost  nature  or  heart, 
and  even  of  our  whole  physico-psychical  constitution  ;  (3) 
that  conscience  must  grow,  and  that  external  revelation  as 
well  as  social  influences  contribute  to  its  complete  develop- 
ment. The  first  two  factors  are  united  in  the  same  general 
way  in  which  a  creative  and  sustaining  cause  is  everywhere 
united  with  a  secondary  cause.^  That  is  to  say,  God's  word 
creates,  but  does  so  for  the  purpose  of  sustaining  the  object 
created,  and  hence  the  latter  must  have  a  life  and  efficacy  of 
its  own,  which  must  not  be  suppressed  by  the  divine  causality. 
The  word  of  God  creates,  and  its  effect  therefore  is,  that 
reason  now  speaks  for  itself  in  the  language  it  has  derived 
from  God.  But  still,  whatever  reason  says  and  knows  is 
given  it  by  God  ;  for  it  says  nothing  that  is  absolutely 
new,  but  only  reproduces  that  which  is  in  the  creative, 
ever-active  will  of  God  ;  it  does  not  simply  give  expression 
to  what  lies  latent  in  the  rational  nature  of  man,  but 
rather  to  what  is  originated  by  the  ever-present  and  living 
operation  of  God,  The  pure  products  of  our  moral  nature 
must  be  regarded  as  being  at  the  same  time  acts    of    God 

^  Pp.  99  sq.,  155  sq.  ^  Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  ii.  §  35,  36. 


§  2a.    STAGES  OF  CONSCIEN-CE,  237 

in  man  ;  all  tlie  more  because  God  is  educating  man,  and  there- 
fore accompanies  every  act  of  pure  moral  perception  with  the 
impulse  of  His  Spirit,  makes  a  claim  upon  and  appeals  to 
what  is  deepest  in  the  nature  of  man.  Accordingly  we  do 
not  employ  a  mere  figure  of  speech,  but  only  indicate  the 
essential  basis  of  moral  legislation,  when  we  say  that  in 
conscience  the  voice  of  God  speaks  to  man  ;  and  this  also 
corresponds  with  what  we  have  already  found,  viz.  that  the 
objective  law  must  be  the  starting-point  of  the  moral  process. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  causality  of  God  only  accomplishes 
this  work  of  legislation  by  its  not  remaining  the  sole  cause 
in  the  matter,  but  by  its  originating  a  secondary  cause,  which 
is  really  different  from  God,  but  which  nevertheless — so  far 
as  conscience  is  truly  developed — derives  its  knowledge  of 
good  and  evil  from  its  connection  unth  Him.  Finally,  with 
regard  to  the  third  factor,  history  and  society  have  their 
claims  acknowledged  when  we  say  that  conscience  passes 
through  a  series  of  stages,  has  a  growth,  and  requires  to  be 
cultivated  like  every  rational  facidty  in  man  ;  and  that  in  this 
growth  it  becomes  more  and  more  enriched  with  an  increasing 
store  of  concrete  material. 

§  2n.  Stages  of  Conscience. 

In  its  first  stage  moral  consciousness  is  not  yet  concrete 
moral  knowledge ;  it  takes  the  form  of  moral  feeling 
and  moral  sense  (§  12.  4;  24(y.  1),  and  is  only 
conscience  m  essence  to  begin  with,  being  no  more 
than  the  perception  of  moral  good  in  general,  as 
distinct  from  evil  and  obligatory.  On  the  second  stage, 
this  fundamental  basis  is  still  preserved,  but  an  advance 
is  now  made  to  concrete  moral  material,  partly  through 
the  influence  of  moral  authorities,  and  partly  tlu'ough 
man's  growing  knowledge  of  himself  and  of  the  world. 
At  the  same  time,  the  various  concrete  duties  which 
now  arise  cannot  as  yet  be  connected  wdth  each  other 
and  with  the  fundamental  moral  knowledge  of  the  first 
stage,  so  as  to  form  a  stable  and  connected  whole.  Hence, 
while  there  is  an  accumulating  mass  of  rules  and  precepts. 


238  §  2,-.    STAGES  OF  COXSCIENCE. 

the  immediate  certainty  of  their  truth  and  moral  necessity 
is  still  awanting.  It  is  not  till  the  third  stage  is  reached 
that  the  concrete  moral  knowledge  of  the  second  can  he 
combined  with  the  elementary  but  fundamental  moral 
knowledge  of  the  first,  in  such  a  way  that  the  multi- 
plicity of  the  former  is  reduced  to  unity,  while  the  unity 
of  the  latter  is  resolved  into  organized  diversity.  It  is  not, 
however,  merely  our  initial  stock  of  moral  knowdedge  that 
is  to  be  regarded  as  due  to  an  act  of  divine  revelation  ; 
for  moral  knowledge  also  in  its  concrete,  more  expanded 
shape  (in  other  words,  conscience)  is  only  possible 
through  continuous  divine  enlightenment  and  revelation 
— the  latter  keeping  pace  with  man's  growing  know- 
ledge of  himself  and  of  the  world, 

1.  The  necessity  of  a  groivth  of  conscience  is  recognised  in 
Holy  Scripture  (Ps.  cxix. ;  Eom,  xii.  2  ;  Phil.  i.  9  ;  Heb.  v, 
14).  No  one  denies  that  wherever  conscience  exists,  there 
is  a  knowledge  of  the  universal  truth  that  the  good,  what- 
ever  form  it  may  take,  ought  to  be  done,  and  evil  to  be 
avoided.  Now,  should  it  be  denied  that  a  growth  of  con- 
science is  nevertheless  necessary,  such  a  position  can  only 
be  maintained  on  one  of  two  suppositions  :  either  that  the 
development  of  conscience  in  the  way  of  acquiring  concrete 
material  is  of  no  moral  importance,  that  its  initial  general 
knowledge  is  sufficient  for  all  moral  purposes  ;  or  else,  that 
man  is  originally  endowed  by  nature  with  the  power  of  arriv- 
ing at  a  clear  decision  on  matters  of  concrete  experience. 

(«)  In  support  of  the  first  of  these,  it  might  be  urged,  that 
the  only  tiling  required  is  really  to  reverence  the  moral  law 
in  general,  to  have  a  good  intention  in  all  we  do,  to  will 
the  good  from  pure  motives  and  without  any  self-seeking. 
When  this  is  the  case,  it  is  all  the  same  what  w^e  do.  It 
is  only  the  form  of  our  acts  that  is  of  importance,  not 
their  contents.^     But    this    would    lead    to    the    maxim  of 

^  This  is  held  even  by  Kant  in  his  GruncUegung  ziir  Metajyhysik  der  Sittcn, 
ed.  by  Rosenkranz,  Werke,  voh  viii.  (pp.  20  sq.,  40,  76,  94).  Ed.  v.  Hart- 
mann  gives  an  excellent  criticism  of  this  view  in  his  Phanomenologie  des 
dtUkhtn  Bewusstseins,  p.  322  sq 


NECESSITY  OF  A  GROWTH  OF  CONSCIENCE.  239 

Jesuitism,  and  would  obliterate  the  distinction  between  good 
and  evil  in  everything  that  is  concrete,  whereas  the  good 
has  no  more  than  a  mere  docetic  existence  when  disjoined 
from  the  concrete.  The  connection  between  the  form  and  the 
contents  of  the  good  is  so  close,  that  the  existence  of  a  pure, 
good  disposition  or  intention  cannot  be  admitted,  unless  that 
which  is  willed  be  right.  Christian  wisdom  is  an  essential 
element  in  good  intentions  and  a  good  disposition.  To  say 
that  it  is  indifferent  what  the  effect  of  our  actions  may  be, 
whether  they  benefit  the  world  or  not,  would  be  equivalent  to 
denying  that  there  is  one  great  moral  task  upon  which  all  are 
engaged,  and  that  the  moral  law  is  the  world-ideal.  In  that 
case,  all  that  would  be  left  for  man  to  do  would  be  to  main- 
tain his  abstract  good  intention,  while  he  remained  indifferent 
to  everything  else.  This  would  be  a  subtle  form  of  egoism. 
In  addition  to  what  has  been  said,  practical  life  would  be 
bereft  of  its  guiding- star  if  conscience  could  never  become 
possessed  of  concrete  knowledge  ;  and  since  man  must  never- 
theless act  in  some  way  or  other,  the  subject,  being  deprived 
of  all  definite  moral  knowledge,  would  be  at  the  mercy  of 
fortuitous  objective  influences  or  of  his  own  subjective 
inclinations. 

(6)  But  just  as  little  can  we  hold,  with  Fichte,  that  con- 
science is  able,  from  the  very  first  and  by  its  own  nature, 
to  solve  all  the  problems  of  practical  life.  We  must  not — 
as  Hirscher  does — regard  even  the  subsequent  conscience  as 
fully  formed  at  the  outset.  A  conscience  may  be  formed, 
but  there  is  no  such  thing  as  one  ready  made.  It  would  be 
iitterly  opposed  to  the  way  in  which  man's  nature  is  constituted 
in  all  other  respects,  were  he  furnished  from  the  first  with 
complete  moral  knowledge,  adequate  for  all  circumstances, — 
circumstances  which  do  not  exist  to  begin  with,  but  which 
successively  arise  and  impose  different  duties  as  he  passes 
through  different  stages  of  life.  Not  only  is  experience 
against  such  a  view,  but  also  the  idea  of  the  ethical ;  for  in 
this  case  wisdom  would  no  longer  be  an  ethical  acquisition,  in 
other  words,  a  virtue.  Moral  knowledge  must  therefore  be 
morally  acquired,  and  conscience  as  given  us  by  nature  must 
undergo  an  ethical  process  of  self-culture,  depending  upon 
reflection   throughout.      On  the   other  hand,  however,  we   do 


240  §  2J,    STAGES  OF  COXSCIENCE.       FIRST  STAGE. 

not  say  that  this  work  of  self-culture  implies  that  conscience 
with  its  originality  and  immediateness  must  rjivc  i^lacc  to  the 
knowledge  which  w^e  acquire  through  reflection.  If  our  in- 
creasing knowledge  of  the  world,  of  ourselves,  and  of  God  be 
brought  into  close  relationship  with  the  idea  of  morality  (and 
for  this  end  the  continued  living  operation  of  the  Divine  Spirit 
is  indispensable),  then  the  enriched  and  cultivated  moral 
consciousness  which  we  thus  obtain  will  recover  at  each  stage 
of  its  progress  that  freshness  and  immediate  power  which  are 
the  characteristics  of  conscience.  And  hence  conscience  will 
lie  able  to  issue  its  decisions  regarding  what  is  concrete  with 
no  less  definiteness  than  regarding  the  general  proposition, 
that  good  ought  to  be  done  and  evil  avoided. 

Accordingly  we  have  arrived  at  the  following  results.  On 
the  one  hand,  conscience  is  not  fully  formed  from  the  first, 
requiring  no  cultivation.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is  not  con- 
iined  to  an  immediate  and  assured  conviction  of  the  validity 
of  the  general  proposition  mentioned  above  ;  it  is  therefore  not 
incapable  of  cultivation,  and  hence  we  are  not  dependent 
upon  authority,  probability  and  prudence  alone  to  guide  us 
in  matters  of  concrete  morality.  Since  this  is  the  case, 
the  full  and  adequate  idea  of  conscience — an  idea  which 
cannot  be  realized  at  once,  but  only  through  a  gradual  process 
— must  be  distinguished  from  the  stacjcs  of  its  realization. 

2.  We  call  the  first  of  these  stages  that  of  con&dcnct  in 
esse7ice,  of  the  possibility  of  the  concrete.  Scholasticism 
designated  conscience  as  it  appears  at  this  stage  by  the  bar- 
barous word  Synderesis,  a  corruption  of  avvTi]pr](7i<i  =  conligatio, 
obligatio,^  the  bond  of  obligation  by  which  we  are  joined  to 
God,  the  essential  bond  between  the  Creator  and  the  rational 
creature.  This  rudimentary  conscience  contains — although 
concrete  circumstances  are  required  to  call  it  into  play — the 
knowledge  of  the  absolute  obligation  imposed  by  the  good  as 
such,  whatever  shape  the  latter  may  take.  Of  conscience  in 
this  form  it  holds  good  most  directly,  that  it  is  the  voice  of 
God.  The  certainty  it  possesses  is  the  type  and  standard  of 
all  moral  certainty.     Moreover,  there  is  also  given  in  it  some- 

1  Cf.  Gass,  i)a-s  (rewisse?!,  Appendix  ;  [also,  G'eschichte  d.  Ghristl.  EtJdk,  i. 
p.  383  sq.— Ed.].  Fr.  Nitzscli,  Uf.her  die  Entstehunn  der  scholastinchen  Lchre 
von  der  Synthcresis.     Jahrhucher  fur  protest.  Tlieologk,  v.  p.  492  sq. 


ADVANCE  TO  CONCRETE  MORALITY,  241 

thing  that  has  a  bearing  upon  the  concrete  moral  life.  We 
learn  from  it  that  nothing  can  be  a  moral  command  which  is 
not  of  an  unconditional  character.  Thus  conscience  even  at 
this  stage  possesses  critical  authority,  though  of  a  negative 
kind  ;  it  can  offer  resistance  to  mere  desire,  when  the  latter 
is  in  opposition  to  the  good.  Accordingly,  even  where  con- 
.science  is  still  deficient  in  cultivation  with  regard  to  what  is 
positively  enjoined,  the  knowledge  of  what  is  forbidden  may 
extend  a  long  way.  We  know  what  is  opposed  to  conscience 
before  we  know  what  is  positively  good.  Scripture  also 
recognises  this  form  of  conscience,  and  recognises  it  as  still 
continuing  to  act  amid  the  perversions  of  man's  moral  nature. 
It  uttered  its  warnings  previous  to  the  fall  (Gen.  iii.  3, 
cf.  ver.  8),  and  after  the  fall  it  still  speaks  (iv.  13,  14). 

3.  Advance  from  the  rudimentary  conscience  to  concrete 
snored  demands. — As  long  as  man  remains  without  a  concrete 
law,  he  runs  the  risk  of  taking  a  wrong  direction,  becoming 
bewildered,  and  falling  a  prey  to  his  own  capricious  fancies. 
He  may,  for  example,  imagine  that  vehement,  sudden  and 
mastering  desires  are  divine  impulses  within  him,  and  thus 
derive  his  rule  of  action  from  mere  natural  inclination.  But 
it  is  a  still  commoner  occurrence  at  this  stage  for  man  to  have 
recourse  to  purely  objective  authorities,  in  order  to  learn  from 
them  what  he  has  to  do  and  what  to  leave  undone.  This  is 
the  origin  of  the  great  influence  exerted  over  the  moral  life 
of  the  ancient  world,  both  private  and  public,  by  divination 
in  the  widest  sense  of  the  word,  including  the  interpretation 
of  dreams,  of  the  flight  of  birds  and  passage  of  clouds,  cxtis- 
picia,  omina,  and  above  all  —  divination  by  oracles.  The 
whole  life  of  heathen  nations  was  held  by  this  practice  as  in 
a  tliick  tangled  net.  We  cannot  refuse,  indeed,  to  acknow- 
ledge that  in  it  there  is  a  moral  element.  In  the  endeavour 
to  learn  the  will  of  the  gods,  we  trace  the  sense  which  man 
has,  that  in  order  to  be  good  he  must  follow  not  his  own  self- 
will,  but  a  higher  objective  law.  But  now,  instead  of  truly 
endeavouring  to  hear  the  voice  of  God  and  to  hold  communion 
with  Him,  man  arbitrarily  takes  nature — as  seen  in  the  sky 
or  on  the  earth — as  his  lawgiver  or  prophet  of  the  divine 
will ;  he  seeks  to  discover  what  result  has  been  pre-ordained, 
and  directs  his  actions  accordingly,  so  that  he  is  not  exclusively 

Q 


242  §  25.    STAGES  OF  CONSCIEKCE. 

concerned  about  doing  what  is  right,  but  about  doing  what  is 
advantageous.  And  arbitrariness  prevails  to  an  equal  extent 
in  the  meaning  attached  to  omens,  which  are  for  the  most 
part  ambiguous  in  themselves.  Hence  it  is  only  a  semblance 
of  objectivity  after  all  at  which  man  has  arrived  in  this  way ; 
his  self-will  is  disguised  as  it  were,  it  has  surrendered  itself  a 
prisoner  to  nature  or  to  particular  natural  phenomena.  It  was 
for  this  reason  that  the  Hebrew  lavj  absolutely  forbade  any 
attempt  being  made  to  find  out  by  means  of  natural  signs, 
stars,  clouds,  or  birds,  what  ought  to  be  done  in  matters  of 
practical  experience.-^  To  do  so  was  regarded  as  a  relapse 
into  nature-worship  and  idolatry.  The  law  is  bent  upon 
setting  men  free  from  such  bondage,  which  threatens  to 
destroy  the  coherence  and  stability  of  moral  life ;  it  seeks  to 
raise  man  above  nature.  Hence,  too,  we  do  not  find  in  the 
New  Testament  a  single  instance,  subsequent  to  the  day  of 
Pentecost,  of  the  lot  being  used  for  the  purpose  of  ascertain- 
ing the  divine  will ;  it  is  only  before  Pentecost  that  such  an 
instance  occurs  (Acts  i.). 

Nevertheless,  even  in  heathendom  the  progressive  cultiva- 
tion of  the  moral  nature  was  not  lost  in  this  abnormal  and 
confusing  tendency.  The  New  Testament  does  not  say  that 
only  conscience  in  its  initial  form  is  to  be  found  among 
the  heathen,  and  that  all  concrete  morality  has  fallen  under 
the  sway  of  self-will  or  accident.  On  the  contrary,  it  is 
expressly  recognised  by  Paul "  that  moral  ideas  and  moral 
ordinances  have  arisen  among  the  heathen.  When  we  inquire 
as  to  the  source  of  these,  we  must  remember  what  has  been 
said  earlier,  viz,  that  the  objective  divine  law  does  not  merely 
form  an  ideal  organism  in  the  divine  mind ;  that  the  endow- 
ment of  man,  both  physically  and  mentally,  for  moral  ends 
does  not  exist  merely  as  part  of  an  ideal  plan  or  decree, 
but  has  actually  been  carried  into  effect  from  the  very 
first, — nay,  more,  that  it  has,  up  to  a  certain  degree,  been 
an  operative  motive  power  in  man,  from  the  beginning  of 
human  life  on  to  the  formation  of  natural  communities 
(§  10-17).  This  explains  the  Pauline  ^vaeu  iroiel  {ja  eOvt]) 
ra  epya  tov  vo/xov.       For,  that    man   is  a  unity   created  in 

1  Ex.  xxii,  18  ;  Lev.  xix    26    31,  xx,  6,  27  ;  Deut.   xviii.   10-14  ;  1  Sam. 
xxviii.  9.  -  Rom.  ii.  12  ff.,  xiii.  1  if. 


E-MPIEICAL  ACQUISITIONS.  243 

the  image  of  God,  that  in  all  the  powers  bestowed  on  him 
liis  moral  destination  has  been  kept  in  view,  that  these 
powers  have  been  harmoniously  ordered  with  reference  to 
it,  so  that  they  cannot  truly  exist  and  flourish  unless  when 
morally  regulated, — this  is  the  ep'yov  vo/jlov  ypairTov  iv  rat'? 
fcapBiac^}  The  work  which  has  to  be  realized  through  the 
agency  of  the  will  is  from  the  first  engraved  upon  the  mental 
organization  of  man  as  something  demanding  fulfilment,  and 
has  therefore  an  innate  tendency  towards  realization. 

And  now,  if,  in  addition  to  this,  there  be  present  that 
fundamental  moral  knowledge  which  we  have  frequently 
alluded  to,  there  arises  of  necessity  a  consciousness  of  ethical 
determination,  and  our  moral  consciousness  becomes  enriched 
from  without,  through  reflection  and  experience.  Of  course 
this  is  by  no  means  the  same  thing  as  a  self-unfolding  of 
conscience  from  within,  it  is  not  as  yet  allied  with  the  certain 
consciousness  of  unconditional  duty.  Man's  knowledge  of 
himself  and  of  the  world  is  extended,  he  gains  an  empirical 
knowledge  of  the  constitution  of  the  world  and  of  man, 
learns  their  powers  and  the  laws  of  their  harmonious  opera- 
tion, and  becomes  acquainted  with  the  conditions  which 
limit  the  sovereignty  and  energy  of  the  will.  Such  know- 
ledge, derived  from  his  own  personal  experience,  is  increased 
by  means  of  the  authority  and  teaching  of  others  whose 
experience  is  wider,  such  as  parents  and  ancestors,  and  by  the 
handing  down  of  wise  sayings,  which,  it  may  be,  are  collected 
and  preserved  as  they  were  at  Delphi.  Thus  we  have,  as 
sources  of  moral  knowledge,  maxims,  proverbs  (Qyt^'P),  and 
didactic  poems,  and  in  addition  to  these,  edrj  and  human 
legislation,  both  of  which  are  of  moral  import.  Thus  man- 
kind gradually  accumulates  a  large  stock  of  moral  ideas  for 
the  different  spheres  of  life,  and  this  takes  place  even  in 
the  heathen  world.  But  the  materials  thus  collected  con- 
tain many  contradictions,  through  their  being  too  strict  or 
too  lax.  Further,  they  cannot  lay  claim  to  the  character 
of  unconditional  necessity,  or  at  least  their  claim  is  not 
indisputable,  since  they  are  not  brought  into  connection 
with  conscience,  and  are  not  recognised  as  good  in  themselves. 
Accordingly,  they  all  have  the  tendency  to  take  the  tone  of 

1  Rom.  ii.  15. 


244  §  25.    STAGES  OF  CONSCIENCE.       APrROITJATION 

mere  prudence,  or  are  simply  counsels  that  never  rise  above 
the  standpoint  of  eudtemonisra. 

We  must  realize  to  ourselves  the  confusion  that  prevailed 
among  the  heathen,  even  among  the  Greeks,  with  regard  to 
moral  ideas,  the  variableness  of  these,  their  instability,  their 
fragmentary  character  (as  depicted,  c.//.,  by  the  Platonic  Socrates 
in  his  disputes  with  the  Sophists  and  the  common  people),  in 
order  to  receive  a  truly  living  impression  of  the  great  blessing 
which  the  law  proved  to  the  Hebrews.  Then  for  the  first 
time  the  unsteadily  flickering  flame  of  moral  knowledge, 
threatened  by  all  the  storms  of  passion,  became  a  steady  and 
certain  light,  through  morality  being  held  aloft  unwaveringly 
by  the  objective  law.  At  the  same  time  the  law  is  not 
something  alien  to  the  inward  nature  of  the  Hebrew  race  ;  it 
expresses  the  true  national  spirit  or  idea,  when  it  brings  the 
individual  and  the  whole  people  alike,  both  inwardly  and 
outwardly,  under  the  lofty  and  yet  simple  idea  of  holiness. 
Nevertheless,  under  the  legal  system  man  is  very  far  from 
arriving  at  that  peculiar  certainty  which  belongs  to  conscience, 
with  reference  to  the  material  commandments  which  the  law 
enjoins.  Accordingly,  Christ  says  with  respect  to  the  Old 
Testament,  that  a  servant  knoweth  not  what  his  lord  doeth ; 
but  whom  the  Son  maketh  free,  he  is  free  indeed.^  The 
Israelite  knew  indeed  that  he  was  laid  under  obligation  to 
the  law  by  reason  of  its  divine  origin,  and  therefore  by  reason 
of  the  formal  authority  attaching  to  the  precepts  handed 
down  from  Moses.  (The  Eoman  Catholic  Church  still  occupies, 
in  principle,  the  same  position.)  But  here  the  contents  of  the 
law  are  not  yet  brought  into  true  union  with  conscience  ; 
man  is  not  yet  an  independent  being,  conscious  of  his  own 
true  nature  and  therefore  free  ;  he  is  still  divided,  dependent 
on  two  principles  which  are  not  yet  united,  the  one  external 
only  and  authoritative,  the  other  internal.  This  is  the  legal 
stage,  on  which  man  does  not  as  yet  perceive  the  unity  of  the 
numerous  precepts  which  are  given  him.  He  may  perhaps 
endeavour  to  discover  among  them  one  precept  which  is 
relatively  the  highest,  but  still  he  fails  to  see  that  this  one  is 
the  sum  of  all  good.  As  the  heathen  world  came  to  recognise 
Zeus  or  Jupiter  as  the  highest  among  the  gods,  so  the  Jewish 

1  John  viii.  32,  xv.  15. 


BY  CONSCIENCE  OF  THE  MATTEK  OF  EXPElilENCE.  245 

world  got  SO  far  as  to  perceive  that  love  is  the  first,  the 
perfect  and  most  excellent  command.  But  just  as  heathendom 
never  got  tlie  length  of  recognising  that  the  highest  deity  is 
also  the  only  one,  comprehending  within  himself  everything 
tliat  is  divine,  so  Judaism  always  fell  short  of  perceiving  that 
all  that  is  good  is  summed  up  in  love. 

4.  It  is  no  doubt  true  that  on  the  stage  of  reflection  an 
effort  is  made  to  overcome  the  contradictions  and  the  frag- 
mentariness  in  which  moral  knowledge  is  involved,  by  working 
up  into  unity  the  manifold  of  ethical  material  which  has 
been  gained  through  experience.  As  tlie  result  of  such 
attempts  we  have  the  picture  of  the  wise  man,  the  picture  of 
the  true  state,  and  codes  of  morals  for  the  various  vocations, 
for  the  sexes,  and  for  tlie  different  stages  of  life.  But  these 
do  not  afford  to  man  complete  personal  certainty  regarding 
moral  rules,  nor  do  they  reveal  to  him  the  inner  unity  of 
the  law.  The  path  which  begins  with  the  rudimentarij 
conscience  must  lead  farther  than  this  empirical  one  does,  if 
man  is  ever,  conscious  of  his  ov/n  true  nature,  to  surrender 
lumself  in  his  concrete  totality  to  the  ethical  idea.  As  his 
self-knowledge  extends  it  makes  him  aware  of  active  and 
receptive  capacities  which  he  possesses,  and  which  are  meant 
to  be  employed  in  the  service  of  the  associations  that  men 
form  by  nature  with  each  other.  These  energies  and  capacities 
are  now  laid  hold  of  by  the  legislative  conscience  on  behalf 
of  the  several  spheres  of  life,  or  in  other  words,  for  the 
purpose  for  which  they  were  given.  Man  perceives  that 
all  these  spheres  have  their  foundations  in  the  constitution 
of  his  own  nature ;  and  thus  he  can  now  recognise  it  as  a 
real  duty  imposed  by  conscience,  to  become  a  member  of 
them,  and  to  conform  himself  to  the  laws  of  life  arising  out  of 
the  specific  nature  of  each  of  them.  The  i'amily  and  the 
State  illustrate  what  has  just  been  said.  And  although  man's 
knowledge  of  these  laws  of  life  is  originally  acquired  through 
experience,  it  can  now  be  taken  up  into  conscience,  and  thus 
merely  empirical  moral  ideas  can  be  transformed,  up  to  a 
certain  degree,  into  a  knowledge  properly  belonging  to  con- 
science. For  example,  when  man  recognises  that  he  is  a  ^wov 
TToXiTLKov  (to  usc  Aristotlc's  phrase),  he  also  knows  that  in 
servinti  the  commonwealth  he  does  that  which  is  rational  and 


246  §  25.    STAGES  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

good,  that  which  corresponds  with  his  own  nature  ;  and  hence 
his  duty  as  a  citizen,  which  at  first  came  to  him  only  as  the 
empirical  demand  of  an  external  authority,  can  now  become  a 
clearly  recofjnised  duty  laid  upon  liiiii  hy  conscience.  And  the 
same  thing  holds  good  witli  regard  to  the  family  and  to 
friendship.  But  in  how  many  ways  does  mere  desire  prove 
stronger  than  the  objective  right  of  these  moral  spheres — for 
example,  in  the  case  of  marriage  (polygamy)  !  Besides,  the 
perception  of  the  good  is  not  yet  accompanied  with  joyful 
pleasure  in  it  and  energy  to  realize  it.  Nevertheless,  the 
more  that  the  matter  of  experience  is  interwoven  with  the 
rudimentary  conscience,  or  the  more  that  conscience  is 
developed,  the  more  comprehensive  it  becomes,  without  its 
suffering  any  loss  of  certainty,  or  falling  under  the  sway 
of  mere  external  authority. 

In  this  way,  too,  conscience  becomes  more  and  more  a 
faithful  mirror  of  that  all-embracing  ideal  organism — the 
objective  law.  Regarded  in  another  light,  this  is  just  the 
process  by  which  conscience  gradually  assimilates  the  objective 
law  of  God.  The  former  is  no  mere  tcd)ida  rasa,  but  embraces 
potentially  every  matter  of  duty;  while,  on  the  other  hand, 
without  this  inward  act  of  enlightenment  on  the  part  of  God, 
that  is  to  say,  without  the  revelation  of  the  law,  conscience 
could  not  grow  nor  even  exist.  It  would  want  that  imniedi- 
ateness  which  must  always  be  accompanied  by  a  divine 
impulse.  Wherever  concrete  moral  material  is  taken  up  and 
united  with  the  rudimentary  conscience,  so  that  the  result 
is  true  subjective-objective  certainty,  such  a  union  must  be 
ascribed  to  the  ever  operative  and  illuminating  power  of  the 
Divine  Spirit  ;  it  is  the  voice  of  God  making  itself  heard 
within.  Accordingly  the  complete  development  of  conscience 
depends  upon  progressive  revelations,  both  internal  and 
external.  More  especially,  the  dvaKecpaXalcoaK  of  the  various 
moral  commandments  into  unity  can  only  be  accomplished, 
and  the  several  moral  regions  of  life  can  only  be  brouglit 
into  organic  connection  with  each  other  by  morality  being 
linked  to  the  idea  of  God,  and  by  God  at  the  same  time 
becoming  known,  in  the  course  of  revelation,  as  that  v/hich 
is  the  sum  of  all  morality — viz.  as  love.  And  this  can 
only    take    place    by    His    revealing    Himself    in    deeds    of 


HEBRAISM  AND  CHEISTIANITY.  247 

love.  For  love  is  known,  not  by  words  or  by  doctrines,  but 
by  actions. 

The  two  religious  communities  which  mark  the  greatest 
progress  that  has  been  made  in  the  sphere  of  morality — the 
Hebrew  and  the  Christian — both  rest,  in  the  most  definite 
way,  on  divine  revelation,  although  they  do  not  maintain 
that  God  has  left  Himself  without  a  witness  to  other  men. 
They  themselves,  again,  are  of  course  very  different.  The 
Old  Testament  revelation  did  not  get  beyond  the  opposition 
between  heathen  and  Jews, — an  opposition  which  is  much 
deeper  than  that  between  Hellenes  and  barbarians, — it  never 
overcame  heathenism,  nor  burst  the  narrow  shell  in  which  a 
universal  principle  lay  hid.  It  was  only  the  perfect  form  of 
revelation  that  could  accomplish  this.  Both  Hebraism  and 
Christianity  represent  the  idea  of  the  unity  of  mankind  ;  for 
both  alike  refer  everything  back  to  God,  and  are  thus  alone 
in  a  position  to  reduce  to  unity  the  countless  contradictions  of 
the  world,  and  to  cause,  as  it  were,  all  natural  differences  to 
disappear.  But  it  was  only  when  revelation  attained  its 
linal  form  in  Christianity  that  it  reached  the  idea  of  a  unity 
which  is  higher  than  the  merely  natural  one,  and  taught  with 
perfect  clearness  that  mankind  as  a  whole  had  one  great 
moral  work  assigned  it.  Accordingly  it  is  not  till  the  con- 
summation of  revelation  that  conscience  is  found  in  its  highest 
form,  objectively  in  Clnist  and  subjectively  in  faith,  which 
on  its  ethical  side  may  be  called  the  Christian  conscience. 
The  spirit  of  love,  which  proceeds  from  Christ  and  addresses 
itself  both  to  the  intelligence  and  the  will,  brings  into  inward 
unity  the  multiplicity  of  duties  and  precepts  ;  it  is  thus  a 
safeguard  against  all  collisions  of  duties,  and  is  the  only 
power  capable  of  enabling  man  to  apprehend  morality  as  an 
organic  unity,  so  that  in  each  single  act  which  he  does  the 
whole  is  included,  since  he  wills  every  act  as  part  of  the 
ethical  whole  or  kingdom  of  God. 

Hence  the  New  Testament  shows  no  ^orcdileciion  for  estab- 
lishing an  objective,  divinely-sanctioned  order  of  life.  It  seeks 
to  conduct  man  to  an  imvarcl  personal  knowledge  of  his  own 
regarding  moral  truth  (John  viii.  32).  An  objective  order  of 
life  which  leaves  out  of  sight  personal  individual  conviction, 
may,  it  is  true,  lay  the   foundation  for  the  formation  of  an 


248  §  25.    STAGES  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

objective  community  of  a  theocratic  or  political  kind, — and 
this  is  the  characteristic  feature  of  antiquity, — but  at  the 
same  time  the  rights  of  the  individual  as  distinguished  from 
those  of  the  whole  community  are  as  yet  imperfectly 
recognised.  The  jSTew  Testament,  on  the  contrary,  makes 
it  its  aim  to  form  conscious,  new  and  free  personalities, 
morally  responsible  each  on  his  own  account.  This  is 
why  it  so  often  makes  it  a  duty  to  strive  after  moral 
certainty  (Eom.  xiv.  1,  13-23;  1  Cor.  viii.  7,  12,  x.  25; 
Col.  ii.  16  ;  Heb.  v.  16  ;  Jas.  i.  6-8,  iv.  8).  He  who 
doubts  is  Bi^jrv^o'i,  whereas  we  ought  to  become  a-TrXot, 
reXeiot  through  i'ree,  complete  union  with  objective  truth. 
'  EKaaTO^  iv  tm  l8ia>  vol'  TrXrjpocfiopeLada)  (Rom,  xiv.  5). 
Hence  we  are  enjoined  to  exercise  forbearance  towards 
weak  and  tender  consciences  (Eom.  xiv.  13  f.  ;  1  Cor. 
X.  25).  Hence,  too,  the  rights  of  the  individual  conscience 
are  acknowledged,  and  that  even  when  it  is  in  error 
(1  Cor.  X.  29,  viii.  10  ff.).  Tlie  Christian  as  such  has  a 
personal  knowledge  of  his  own  concerning  objective  good, 
allied  with  inward  certainty  ;  he  carries  in  himself  a  higher 
than  the  merely  subjective  form  of  moral  consciousness 
(1  Cor.  iv.  3  ff.),  something  higher  than  the  current  opinion 
of  the  world ;  he  has  the  spirit  of  wisdom,  which  invests 
him  with  <yv(bcrc<i,  eTrlyvaxTL^;,  and  the  alaOrjrrjpca  yefyufxvaajjieva 
(Heb.  V.  14).  This  ao(f)La  comes  from  faith,  in  so  far  as  the 
latter,  formally  regarded,  is  certainty  of  a  divine  yet  human 
kind,  and  in  so  far  as  the  contents  of  this  certainty  ai-e 
derived  from  the  moral  archetype  and  principle  of  the 
kingdom  of  God  which  is  given  us  in  Christ  (Eph.  v.  14). 
United  to  Christ  we  are  united  to  God,  and  therefore  the 
Christian  conscience  is  always  in  the  presence  of  God  and 
is  manifest  to  Him  (2  Cor.  v.  10,  i.  12  ;  Tit.  i.  15  ;  1  Pet.  ii. 
19,  iii.  21). 

§   26.  Forms  of  the  Manifestation  of  Conscience. 

According  to  the  relation  in  which  it  stands  to  an  act,  three 
forms  of  conscience  are  to  be  distinguished — antecedent, 
concomitant,  and  subsequent.  (Conscientia  antecedens, 
concomitans,  subsequens.) 


§  2G.    FORMS  OF  THE  MANIFESTATION  OF  CONSCIENCE.      249 

1.  The  antecedent  is  its  legislative  form,  and  on  this  suhjecc 
we  have  already  spoken  at  sufficient  length.  Previous  to 
the  act  it  warns  and  dissuades  more  than  it  urges  or  com- 
mands us,  it  checks  or  prohibits  our  impulses.  When  the 
human  will  turns  to  the  good  and  accepts  it,  there  begins 
that  union  of  moral  necessity  and  freedom  in  which  conscious 
morality  consists.  Still,  more  is  required  than  that  conscience 
should  merely  look  on  and  keep  watch  from  the  outside. 
It  must  become  incorporated  with  the  will,  in  order  that  it 
may  be  immanent  in  it  and  serve  as  a  light  to  it.  The 
contents  of  a  deliverance  of  conscience,  however,  are  given 
us  in  the  form  of  a  moral  impulse  from  above,  which  does  not 
constrain  us  like  a  physical  force,  but  comes  forward  in  the 
shape  of  an  unconditional  claim. 

2.  The  concomitant  depends  upon  the  antecedent  form  of 
conscience,  and  is  the  continuation  of  the  latter.  It  may, 
however,  become  obscured  and  weakened  in  the  course  of  the 
act  which  we  perform,  should  that  act  be  one  wliich  is  opposed 
to  conscience.  In  that  case,  conscience  resists  what  we  do, 
and  our  volition  effects  a  division  in  our  nature.  On  the 
contrary,  we  retain  our  unity  and  energy  when  what  we  will 
and  do  is  at  one  with  conscience. 

3.  Conscience  as  subsequent  has  three  functions,  which 
have  been  comprehended  under  the  name  of  the  Sijllogismus 
eonscientice.  Here  the  major  premiss  is  formed  by  intro- 
ducing the  moral  law,  the  minor  by  its  application  to  the 
particular  case  in  point  (imputation),  and  then  the  verdict 
and  requital  of  conscience  follow  as  the  conclusion.  Where 
no  respect  is  paid  to  the  major  premiss  in  conscience,  in  its 
general  bearing,  we  say  there  is  an  utter  want  of  conscience  ; 
where  the  law  is  indeed  recognised  in  general  but  not  in 
concrete,  we  say  that  conscience  is  wide  or  lax  ;  where  im- 
putation is  awanting,  and  we  seek  to  lay  the  guilt  upon  some- 
thing outside  ourselves,  conscience  is  said  to  be  partial ;  and 
where  conscience  or  the  moral  consciousness  upbraids  a  man 
with  guilt  when  no  guilt  exists,  it  is  called  scrupulous. 
Nevertheless  it  is  evident  from  what  has  been  previously 
said  that  in  no  case  is  conscience  a  mere  operation  of  the 
understanding.  We  shall  dwell  for  a  little  upon  conscience 
as  it  appears  in  the  acts  of  im^mtation,  judgment,  and  requited. 


250      §  26.    FORMS  OF  THE  MANIFESTATION  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

Iiiqmtatioii  is  the  consciousness  of  the  relation  in  which 
our  causality  stands  to  the  law.  It  subsumes  under  the  law 
that  whicli  has  to  be  judged  ;  it  presupposes  therefore  a 
standard,  and  something  to  which  that  standard  is  to  be 
applied,  something  submitted  to  moral  evaluation,  and  there- 
fore such  a  thing  as  the  will  can  be  responsible  for.  For 
that  which  is  a  matter  of  purely  physical  necessity,  that 
which  can  in  no  wise  be  made  subject  to  the  will,  whether 
in  the  past,  the  present,  or  the  future,  cannot  without  excessive 
scrupulosity  be  made  a  matter  of  imputation.  Imputation 
presupposes  freedom  of  will,  although  this  does  not  mean 
that  it  is  free  at  every  moment.  Through  evil  having  become 
a  habit,  or  through  guilty  ignorance,  man  may  have  deprived 
himself,  for  the  moment  at  least,  of  freedom  of  action,  without 
being  on  that  account  absolved  from  responsibility  for  what  he 
does.  Imputation,  moreover,  and  moral  judgment  refer  not 
merely  to  single  deeds,  but  also  to  the  character  which  they 
help  to  form.  Imputation  fastens  on  the  individual  act  as 
that  which  brings  it  into  play,  but  it  is  the  person  as  a  whole 
to  whom  the  individual  act  is  imputed.  In  imputation  the 
evil  deed  is  referred  back  to  the  inner  totality  of  man  in 
such  a  way,  that  it  is  declared  to  be  his  peculiar  property,  to 
be  the  fruit  of  his  whole  personality,  and  consequently  to  be 
something  which  burdens  and  pollutes  the  person  as  a  unity. 
Since  imputation  is  thus  directed  to  man  as  a  whole,  there  is 
directly  associated  with  it  a  moral  feeling  affecting  the  wliole 
man.  Through  the  imputation  of  evil,  man  feels  that  he  is 
in  a  condition  wherein  he  is  accused  and  has  an  evil  con- 
science ;  and  imputation,  guided,  as  it  were,  ly  the  individual 
act,  goes  back,  when  conscience  is  lively,  to  the  xinderlying 
character  out  of  ivhieh  the  aet  arose.  Consequently  guilt  and 
responsibility  are  not  escaped  even  when  the  act  is  preceded 
by  a  condition  of  relative  unfreedom.  And  although  this 
state  of  matters  cannot  at  the  moment  be  changed  or  avoided, 
still,  absolutely  regarded,  it  is  avoidable,  and  it  is  the  duty  of 
man  to  effect  the  change.  For  evil  remains  as  a  constant 
contradiction  to  his  eternal  being.  At  the  same  time  there 
are  certainly  degrees  of  imputation,  according  to  the  amount 
of  knowledge  and  will-power  that  enter  into  the  deed. 

That  general  feeling  just  mentioned,  in  which  the^  evil  act 


AN  ERRING  CONSCIENCE.  251 

is  referred  to  the  person  as  a  whole,  marks  the  beginning  of 
the  recoil  of  evil  against  the  evil-doer:  evil  is  something 
'wliiclh  noiv  helongs  to  him  as  a  ixrson.  ]\Iore  or  less  plainly 
it  seizes  upon  his  existence  as  a  whole,  and  this  calls  forth  a 
reaction  on  the  part  of  his  true  being,  of  his  moral  nature, 
which  for  its  own  self-preservation  must  now  separate  itself 
from  the  sin-stained  nature  and  assume  an  attitude  of  accusa- 
tion towards  it  (Rom.  ii.  15).  This  accusation  is  followed 
immediately  by  moral  self-condemnation,  or  an  act  oi  judgment 
on  the  part  of  conscience,  in  which  an  element  of  retribution 
is  involved  (1  John  iii,  19,  20).  In  this  way  we  have  a 
good  or  an  evil  conscience ;  in  the  former  case  there  is  a 
pleasurable  feeling,  the  feeling  of  peace  associated  with  it", 
while  in  the  latter  there  is  the  consciousness  that  evil  is  now 
something  of  its  own,  and  this  gives  it  inward  torment. 
Evil  deeds  are  like  evil  powers,  now  slumbering  now  roused 
into  hostile  activity  against  man ;  and  hence  we  read  of  stings 
of  conscience  (1  Tim.  iv.  2),  and  of  self-condemnation  (1  John 
iii.  20). 

4.   In  conclusion,  a  word  must  still  be  said  as  to  whether 

there  is  such  a  thing  as  an  erring  conscience,  which  we  ought 

nevertheless   to    obey.       Conscience   in    the  true    sense,  not 

merely  what   aiopcars   to  be   conscience,  cannot  possibly   err. 

For  God's  voice  cannot  contradict  itself.     In  accepting  what 

is  false  we  cannot  possibly  have  a  ijcrsoncd  conviction  of  its 

truth,  although  we  may  have  a  very  lively  trust  in  external 

authorities.       For    if   a    falsehood    could    invest    itself  with 

certainty  just    as  much  as  a  truth,  there  would    no    longer 

be  any  certainty  with  regard  to  truth.     The  same  thing  is 

clear   from   the  fact  that  all  erroneous   moral   ideas  can  be 

overcome.     This  can  be  done  only  because  it  can  be  shown 

that  they  are  in  contradiction  to  something  better,  something 

which  may  sleep  but  can  be   awakened.       Neither  can  the 

opinion  that  erring  consciences  do  exist  find  shelter  behind 

Scripture.      Paul,  it  is  true,  acknowledges  that  the   conscience 

of  each  individual  has  its  special  modifications  (e/cao-ro?  iv  tu) 

lBIq)   vol  7r\7]po^op6ta6o3,  Horn.  xiv.   5  ;   1    Cor.  x.   29).      He 

speaks  too  of  weak  consciences,  Eom.  xiv.  15,  and  demands, 

on  behalf  both   of  the  individual   conscience  and  the   weak 

conscience,   that   no   offence  be   given  them.      For   example, 


2  52      §  26.    FOliMS  OF  THE  MANIFESTATIOX  OF  CONSCIENCE. 

whoever  has  scruples  about  eating  flesh,  especially  flesh 
oftered  to  idols,  ought — even  leaving  out  of  sight  the  fact 
that  there  are  others  whose  consciences  should  not  be  offended 
— to  abstain  from  eating ;  he  must  not,  by  doing  that  which 
his  moral  consciousness  declares  to  be  sinful  or  doubtful, 
assume  to  himself  a  higher  degree  of  moral  freedom  and 
knowledge  than  that  which  he  has  properly  attained.  His 
duty  is  rather  to  devote  his  energies  to  growth  in  moral 
knowledge,  before  he  exercises  his  freedom  in  such  innocent 
matters.  But  although  Paul  certainly  says  that  we  ought 
not  to  act  inconsistently  with  the  degree  of  moral  knowledge  we 
have  attained,  he  does  7wt  say  that  we  ought  to  follow  the 
false  declarations  and  demands  of  an  ostensible  conscience 
when  it  asks  us  to  do  that  which  is  evil  in  itself.  A  Jew,  for 
example,  may  believe  that  he  is  doing  God  service  in  per- 
secuting or  slaying  Christians,  and  a  heathen  may  believe  that 
lie  is  permitted  or  enjoined  by  his  religion  to  drown  his  child 
in  the  Ganges,  but  it  is  the  duty  neither  of  Jew  nor  heathen 
to  do  that  which  objectively  is  wrong.  Wherever  a  spurious 
conscience  would  make  something  that  is  evil  a  matter  of 
duty,  the  missionary  must  boldly  demand  that  the  supposed 
duty  be  not  discharged,  that  a  thing  which  is  evil  in  itself  be 
not  done. 

The  only  case  in  which  it  is  a  duty  to  follow  the  dictates 
of  an  erring  moral  consciousness  is  when  our  major  premiss 
is  correct,  —  viz.  that  evil  ought  to  be  avoided,  —  but  an 
erroneous  minor  premiss  has  been  brought  under  it ;  and  even 
then  this  holds  good  only  with  reference  to  our  abstaining 
from  the  exercise  of  a  freedom  for  which  we  are  not  yet 
prepared.  In  such  a  case  an  erring  moral  consciousness  may 
declare  that  it  is  morally  doubtful  whether  we  ought  to 
exercise  our  freedom,  and  therefore  that  we  ought  to  refrain 
from  doing  so  ;  and  here  it  cannot  be  said  that  it  is  sinful 
to  abstain  from  using  our  freedom  (cf.  Eom.  xiv.  1  ff . ;  1  Cor. 
viii.  7  ff.,  X.  23—33).  But  when  the  matter  in  question  is 
something  evil  which  is  enjoined  by  an  erring  moral  con- 
sciousness, then  we  must  say  that  it  can  never  be  so  closely 
associated  with  moral  certainty  as  to  make  its  performance  a 
duty.  That  evil  should  put  itself  forward  as  something  good 
is   in  itself  quite  unnatural,  and   hence   a  truer  knowledge 


§  27.    FREEDOM.  253 

finds  entrance  into  the  mind  when  an  appeal  is  made  to  a 
higher  consciousness,  to  that  which  really  is  conscience  and 
which  affords  true  certainty,  a  certainty  allied  with  that 
originality  and  immediateness  which  go  with  convictions  of 
the  higliest  kind.  Accordingly  there  is  a  confusion  of  con- 
science with  inorcd  consciousness  in  general  when  it  is  held 
that  we  may  speak  of  an  erring  conscience.  We  formerly 
saw  that  the  moral  consciousness,  especially  at  its  second 
stage,  is  liable  to  great  aberrations,  although  it  may,  at  the 
same  time,  have  a  high  degree  of  faith  in  the  trustworthiness 
and  authority  of  its  objective  source.  But  such  an  erring 
moral  consciousness  lacks  that  ivhich  is  the  special  character- 
istic of  conscience — viz.  true,  immediate  certainty  with  regard 
to  morality  in  itself  and  independent  of  external  authorities. 
Conscience,  indeed,  is  often  introduced  into  matters  with  which 
it  has  nothing  to  do  ;  but  this,  even  where  it  is  done  in  good 
faith,  is  arbitrary  autonomy,  and  in  truth  nothing  but 
Antinomianism. 

THIED   SECTION. 

FKEEDOM. 


The  doctrines  which  liave  been  held  regarding  freedom  range 
themselves  historically  under  the  antithesis  of  Deter- 
minism and  Indeterminism  ;  an  antithesis  which  passes 
through  various  stages.  The  lower  forms  of  both  always 
incline  to  run  into  each  other,  a  fact  which  proves  that 
the  members  of  the  antithesis  tend  towards  one  another, 
each  of  them  representing  a  side  of  truth  which  strives 
after  union  with  the  otlier  side.  Accordingly  the  goal 
to  which  science  has  to  approximate  is  to  combine  both 
of  them  in  a  higher  unity. 

Literature. — riato,  De  Bepuhlica,  Bk.  ix.  Origen,  Uspi  apy^Zv. 
Ale.vander  Aphrodisias  and  Ammonius — de  fato — -svrote  on  the 
fatalism,  especially  of  an  astrological  kind,  which  was  so  widely 
spread  in   the  first  centuries.     Ephrcm   Syrus  wrote  on   the 


25-t  §  27.    FKEEDOM.       LITERATURE. 

other  side.  (Cf.  regarding  these  authors  the  treatise  of  Joh. 
Conr.  Orelli,  Zurich  1824.)  Diodorus  of  Tarsus,  Theodore  of 
Mopsuestia,  Augustine,  Be  libero  arhitrio  ;  c.  Faustum  Manicli- 
amm.  Gemistos  Plethon,  cf.  H.  Grotius,  1648,  Pliilosopliorum 
ccterum  sentcnticc  de  fato.  Of  writers  belonging  to  the  JNIiddle 
Ages,  Thomas  Aquinas  approaches  Determinism,  while  Duns 
Scotus  is  an  Indeterminist ;  Laurentius  Valla  and  Thomas 
Bradwardinus,  however,  are  predestinarians.  In  the  age  of  the 
Eeformation,  we  have  Luther,  De  servo  arhitrio  ;  Erasmus,  De 
libera  arhitrio;  Melanchthon's  Loci,  1521;  Calvin's  Institutio, 
L.  i.  ii.  Besides  several  treatises,  Zwingli,  On  the  Eternal 
Providence  of  God.  Jonathan  Edwards,  one  of  the  most  acute 
of  Calvinists,  An  Inquiry  into  the  Modern  ^prevailing  Notions 
respecting  the  Freedom  of  Will.  W.  King,  in  his  De  originc 
mali,  is,  on  the  other  hand,  an  Indeterminist. 

On  the  philosophical  side  we  may  mention  Spinoza's  Mhil; 
the  Theodicy  of  Leibnitz,  who  conceives  everything  as  under 
divine  predestination,  and  regards  evil  as  limitation.    Material- 
istic fatalism  is  defended  in  the  Systeme  de  la  nature  of  Baron 
von  Holbach.     The  Indeterminism  of  Kant  in  his  Critique  of 
the  Practical  Reason,   and  his   Peligiooi  within  the  Limits  of 
Pure  Reason,  forms   the  transition  to  Schelling's  doctrine   of 
the  predeterminism  of  freedom.     Daub,  Judas  Iscariot,  2  vols. ; 
as    well    as    his    DarstcUung    und    Beurtheilung   der    Hypo- 
thesen  in  Betreff  der  Willensfreihcit,  1834,  and  his  Christliche 
Moral.      Bockshammer,    Uel)er   die   Freiheit    des    menschlichen 
Willcns,  1821.     Franz  v.  Baader,  Begriindung  der  Ethik  durch 
Physik,  1843.     Herbart,   Praldisehe  Philosophic  {die  Idee   der 
inner  en  Freiheit),   Werke,  vol.  viii.  p.  33   sq.,  vol.  ix.  Nr.  9  ; 
Gesprdeh  ilher  das  Bose,  1847.     Vatke,  Die  menschliche  Freiheit, 
1841.     Zeller,  Ueher  die  Freiheit  des  menschlichen  Willens,  das 
Bose  und  die  moralische  Weltordnung,  Theol.  Jahrh.  v.  3,  vi.  1,  2. 
Schleiermacher,   Ueher   die   Erwdldungslchre,  1819.      Eomaug, 
Willensfreihcit  und  Determinismus,  1835.    Sigwart,  Das  ProUcrn 
der  Freiheit  und  Unfreiheit  des  menschlichen  Willens,  in  Tiibinger 
Zeitschrifi,  1839,  3.     [Sigwart,  Der  Bcgriff  des  Willens  und  sein 
Verhdltniss  zum  Begriff  der   Ursachc,  1879.- — -Ed.]     Heinrich 
Eitter,  Ueher  das  Bose.     Julius  Miiller,  Doctrine  of  Sin,  with  a 
survey  of  the   different   theories.     Luthardt,  Die   Lehre  vorn 
freicn  Willen.     Eothe,  Ethik,  2nd  ed.  §  86,  p.  349.     Trendelen- 
burg, Naturrecht,  1860,  p.  65  sq.,  §  43 ;  Hist.  Beitrdge  zur  Phil. 
ii.  112;  JSfothwendigkeit  tend  Freiheit  in  der  griechischen  Philo- 
sophie.     Scholten,  Ueher  Willensfreihcit,  translated  by  Manchot, 
1874,  and  criticized  by  Gloatz,  Jahrh.  filr  deutsche  Theol.  1874. 
[Hoekstra,  Vrijheid  in  verhand  met  zclfhewusthcid  zcdelijkhcid 
en  zonde.     Secretan,  La  philosophic  de  la  liherte,  1849.     J.  C. 


ABSOLUTE  PHYSICAL  DETEEMINISM.  255 

Fischer,  Uebcr  die  Frcilhcit  dcs  mcnscMichen  Willcns,  1858. 
Stuart  Mill,  System  of  Deductive  and  Inductive  Logic,  vol.  ii. 
Book  6.  Liebmann,  Ucher  den  individuellen  Beivcis  fur  die 
Freiheit  dcs  Willens,  1866.  J.  B.  Meyer,  PhilosopJiische  Zeit- 
fragen,  cap.  8.  Goering,  Uelcr  die  menschliche  Freiheit,  1876. 
Fluegel,  Prohleme  dcr  Philosophie,  2  Thl.  1876.  H,  Sommer, 
TJeher  das  Wesen  und  die  Bedcutung  der  menschlichen  Freiheit, 
Preussische  JahrhiXcher,  1881,  Nr.  vi.  Zart,  Bemerkungen  zur 
Theorie  der  menschlichen  Freiheit,  1883  ;  Der  christliche  Glauhe 
und  die  mensehliehe  Freilicit,  1880.  Lotze,  MikroJcosmiis,  III, 
Grundzilge  der  praktischen  Philosophie,  p.  16  sq.  Witte,  Ucher 
Freiheit  des  Willens,  1882.  Harms,  Metaphysih,  1885,  pp.  80- 
100.     Of.  besides  the  literature  given  above,  p.  29  sq. — Ed,] 


J.— FIRST  FORM  OF  THE  ANTITHESIS.     ABSOLUTE   PHYSICAL 
DETERMINISM  AND  ABSOLUTE  INDETERMINISM. 

I.    DETERMINISM  IN  ITS  LOWEST  FORM, 

(a)  The  lowest  stage  of  determinism  is  mechanical  deter- 
minism, represented  in  antiquity  by  the  atomists,  and  in 
modern  times  by  Holbach  in  his  Systhne  de  la  nature.  It 
may  take  a  materialistic  shape,  denying  the  distinct  existence 
of  the  soul,  and  regarding  it  as  a  mere  quality  or  activity  of 
matter,  the  highest  form  which  matter  assumes.  Determinism 
of  this  kind  has  been  already  discussed  (§  9.  3).  Substan- 
tially the  same  view  is  held  when  the  existence  of  a  human 
soul  is  admitted,  but  it  is  conceived  as  moved  and  determined 
solely  from  the  outside,  l)y  surrounding  physical  things  or 
forces,  such  as  food,  climate,  or  even  social  relations.  But 
indeterminism  now  comes  forward  with  its  consciousness  of 
freedom,  and  points  with  justice  to  the  ignoble  elements 
contained  in  this  idea.  It  says :  if  man  were  moved  solely 
and  simply  from  the  outside,  if  he  offered  no  resistance  nor 
counteraction  to  external  forces,  then  he  would  be  as  good  as 
non-existent,  he  would  have  no  separate  life  of  his  own. 
For  otherwise  he  would  not  be  merely  determined  and 
conditioned  by  things  external  to  him,  but  would  himself  be 
a  conditioning  power,  in  accordance  with  the  constitution  of 
his  nature.  And  the  very  form  of  determinism  which  we  are 
here  considering  must  admit  that  man  is  such  a  power,  since 
it  holds  that  everything  conditions  every  other,  in  an  endless 


256      §  27.    FREEDOM.       DETERMINISM  IN  ITS  LOWEST  FORM. 

chain  of  influence.  Were  man  not  a  conditioning  cause,  he 
would  be  something  less  than  nature.  But  he  is  spirit,  and 
susceptible  to  the  universal,  and  is  thus  raised  far  above 
mere  dependence  on  the  individual  natural  existences  and 
forces  which  surround  him. 

(b)   Should  determinism  concede  this,  as  it  must,  it  may 
nevertheless  endeavour  to  maintain  itself  by  assuming  a  higher 
form    than    the    mechanical.       Accordingly,    when    a    more 
coherent  method  of  thought  is  adopted,  there  arises  the  idea 
of    a   universal    connection    in    nature,  in    which    all   natural 
forces  are   bound  together  in  a  necessary  chain  of  cause  and 
effect.     Here   it   is  asserted   that   the  principle   of  this   all- 
embracing  and  determining  necessity  is  eifiapfiivr},  fate.      Thus 
mechanical  determinism  passes  over  into  fatalism  ;  man  is  not 
subordinated  to  the  external  forces  of  nature,  but  is  placed 
on  the  same  level  with   them,  and  fate  determines  him  as  it 
does   everything.      But   indeterminism   again    brings   forward 
the  sense  of  freedom  in  opposition  to  fatalism,  and  maintains 
that  it  is  not  only  lowering,  but  also  untrue  to  hold  that  we 
are   dependent   upon   blind,  unconscious   fate,   since   we   are 
conscious  tliat  there  is  within  us  a  causal  poivcr.      If  by  fate 
we  mean  that  nexus  of  cause  and  efifect  by  which  the  whole 
system  of  nature  is  held  together,  and  which  acts  in  the  way 
of  sheer  compulsion,  then  in  this  sense  fate  cannot  exist  for 
man.     For    man    is    conscious    that    he    has    the    power   to 
acquiesce  in  or  to  reject  the  natural  influences  by  which  he 
is   surrounded,  and  that  in   both   cases   he   acts   as  a  being 
endowed  with  will.     The  impulses  which  come  to  him  from 
the   side   of   nature — whether  individually  or  collectively — 
only  exert  a  causal  efficacy  upon   him  through  the   instru- 
mentality of  his  will,  and  therefore,  since  he  can  take  up  an 
attitude  of  independence  towards  the  whole  of  nature,  they 
really  derive  their  power  from  the  spirit  of  man,  so  that  the 
spirit  never  ceases  to  be  its  own  master.      The  spirit  is  no 
mere   unit   among   the   things   of  nature,  and   accordingly   it 
must   not  be  taken  captive   against  its  will  by  any  one   of 
these ;  it  can  always  retire  from  among  them  into  the  depths 
of  its  own  universal  nature,  and  through  its  power  of  self- 
reflection — a  power  which  nature  does  not  possess — take  up 
an  attitude  of  indifference  to  everything  outside  itself.      This 


DETERMINISM.      INDETERMINISM  IN  ITS  FIRST  FORM.         257 

is  the  roclc  on  which  every  form  of  causality  splits,  which 
would  determine  the  spirit  from  without. 

(c)  The  deterministic  mode  of  thought  may  now,  in  order 
to  maintain  itself  against  indeterminism,  attempt  to  find  from 
its  own  point  of  view  a  place  for  the  causality  of  man.  It 
may  say — it  is  just  when  man  realizes  that  everything  outside 
him,  and  he  himself  as  well,  are  dependent  upon  an  all- 
embracing  fate,  that  he  becomes  aware  that  in  the  last  resort 
he  is  not  dependent  upon  external  things,  but  is  independent 
over  against  them  and  free.  They  and  the  whole  system  of 
nature  are  powerless  to  affect  him  in  opposition  to  fate,  which 
assigns  to  him  and  them  their  measure  of  power  and  perma- 
nence, of  right  and  law.  Nay,  more  has  been  assigned  to 
man  than  to  nature.  He  is  a  spiritual  being  of  a  universal 
kind,  and  the  spiritual  world  is  his.  Hence,  collective 
nature  cannot  become  master  of  this  his  universal  and 
essential  being.  Thus  he  is  free  with  respect  to  nature,  but 
is  undoubtedly  subject  to  fate  as  the  law  which  lays  the 
whole  universe  under  the  bonds  of  necessity. 

Here  too  indeterminism  has  its  answer  ready.  Such  a 
power  of  resistance  and  such  an  independence  of  nature  is 
2iot  yet  the  freedom  which  morality  requires.  If  everything 
be  determined  by  fate,  if  even  the  causative  power  of  freedom, 
the  consciousness  and  the  exercise  of  it,  be  so  determined, 
then  freedom  itself  is  denied,  and  also  all  independence  and 
responsibility.  Fate  can  never  consist  with  freedom,  since  it 
is  blind  and,  so  far  as  its  contents  are  concerned,  mere 
motiveless  chance,  which  affords  no  room  for  the  stability  of 
a  coherent  moral  life.  Accordingly  indeterminism,  which  we 
have  hitherto  known  merely  as  the  critic  of  certain  forms  of 
determinism,  advances  a  theory  of  its  own  in  the  following 
shape. 

II.   INDETERMINISM  IN  ITS  FIRST  AND  BAREST  FORM. 

Here  freedom  is  defined  as  the  power  possessed  by  man,  in 
accordance  with  his  universal  nature,  of — if  not  actually 
effecting,  yet — willing  or  not  willing  whatever  is  possible ; 
negatively,  it  is  absolute  freedom  from  everything  like  deter- 
mination or  specific  character.     For  every  determination,  even 

E 


258       §  27.    FREEDOJL       INDETERMINISM  IN  ITS  LOWEST  FOEM. 

though  originally  it  should  take  place  through  man's  own  wil], 
would  be  a  limitation  of  freedom  considered  as  the  faculty  of 
willing  or  not  willing  whatever  is  possible.  Duns  Scotus, 
W.  King  {De  originc  mali),  and  Episcopius  ^  approach  most 
closely  to  this  form  of  indeterminism.  According  to  it, 
freedom  consists  in  the  mere  infinite  ahility  of  willing,  as 
opposed  to  every  definite  volition,  and  therefore  in  the 
capability  of  emancipating  one's  self  from  everything  that 
determines  volition. 

But  here  determinism  can  now  come  forward,  and  point  out 
with  justice  to  this  form  of  indeterminism,  that  it  must  yield 
although  unwillingly  to  determinism,  and  must  even  swing 
round  altogether  into  the  latter.  The  indeterminism  which, 
in  the  interest  of  absolute  freedom  or  of  the  unlimited  ability 
to  will,  holds  that  determinateness  of  every  kind  must  be 
excluded,  confounds  the  infinitum  with  the  indefinitum.^ 
Moreover,  this  indeterminism,  which  thinks  that  freedom  must 
consist  in  complete  exemption  from  every  kind  of  determinate- 
ness, would  also  be  incapable  of  any  definite  volition  or  action. 
The  necessity  would  lie  upon  it,  like  a  fate,  of  willing  nothing 
at  all,  since  every  act  must  involve  a  definite,  individual 
volition.  Did  freedom  merely  consist  in  the  infinite  power  to 
will  whatever  is  possible,  then  man,  when  he  willed  something 
definite,  would  for  the  time  being  lose  his  freedom.  For  he 
cannot,  like  God,  will  everything  that  is  possible  at  one  and 
the  same  moment,  but  can  only  will  some  individual  thing, 
and  this  is  not  commensurate  with  that  universal  ability  of 
which  we  are  speaking,  i.e.  with  freedom  in  the  indeterministic 
sense.  Since  in  every  definite  act  of  volition  freedom  must 
limit  itself  for  the  sake  of  some  individual  thing  which  is 
willed,  the  exercise  of  freedom  would,  according  to  the  notion 
of  it  supplied  by  absolute  indeterminism,  be  identical  with  its 
loss.  So,  in  order  not  to  suffer  such  a  falling  away  from 
itself,  freedom  would  have  to  take  up  a  negative  attitude 
towards  all  the  demands  that  are  addressed  to  it ;  it  would 
necessarily  remain  merely  an  infinite  possibility  or  potency  of 

^   Tractatus  de  libero  arhitrio.     Cf.  Rothe,  2nd  ed.  i.  p.  354. 

^  The  same  fault  lies  in  the  proposition  of  Spinoza  :  omnis  determinatio  est 
negatio ;  and  the  systems  of  Schopenhauer  and  E.  v.  Hartmann  rest  on  the 
same  fundamental  error. 


ABSOLUTE  INDETEEMINISM.  259 

volition,  would  never  will  anything  at  all,  but  would  have  con- 
stantly to  abstain  from  willing.  But  a  potency  of  volition 
which  at  the  same  time  involved  the  impossibility  of  volition 
would  be  a  contradiction.  And  this  shows  that  absolute 
indeterminism  does  not  attain  to  real  freedom,  and  more,  that 
by  thus  falling  back  upon  mere  ability  it  can  never  enjoy  its 
freedom,  nor  assert  its  consciousness  of  it. 

Accordingly,  determinism  is  right  when  it  urges  that  the 
following  inferences  How  from  indeterminism.  Since  the 
latter  thus  stubbornly  rejects  all  definite  contents,  since — in 
order  not  to  shake,  even  for  a  moment,  freedom  as  it  con- 
ceives of  it,  i.e.  the  universal  infinite  possibility  of  volition — 
it  excludes  all  and  every  determination,  even  determination 
mediated  through  the  will  itself,  then  it  follows  that  not  only 
as  a  matter  of  fact  is  no  exercise  of  freedom  possible,  but  also 
that  if  freedom  of  this  kind  is  to  be  preserved,  it  must  have 
imposed  upon  it  like  a  fate  the  necessity  of  willing  nothing 
at  all.  But  such  a  freedom  is  immured  within  itself,  is 
absolutely  powerless,  the  very  opposite  of  freedom.  Hence 
absolute  indeterminism  swings  round  into  its  opposite.  There 
is  no  constancy  in  it.  In  order  that  real  freedom  may  exist, 
it  must  not  be  deprived  of  definite  contents  ;  just  as  the  latter, 
on  the  other  hand,  must  not  abolish  freedom.  On  the 
contrary,  in  order  that  there  may  be  freedom,  the  form  of  free 
volition  must  be  compatible  with  definite  contents.  Neither 
must  freedom  be  made  to  consist  in  indifference  towards  and 
exclusion  of  definite  contents.  Otherwise  it  would  merely  be 
the  power  of  exercising  caprice.  And  caprice  is  just  chance 
in  a  subjective  form. 

That  must  be  a  false  idea  of  freedom  which  surrenders 
freedom — meant  as  it  is  for  action,  for  exercise — to  the 
necessity  either  of  inaction  or  else  of  self-loss.  Fatalism  of 
this  kind,  in  which  absolute  indeterminism  has  landed,  is 
now  opposed  by  another  form  of  determinism,  in  which  the 
mechanical  stage  has  been  recognised  as  untenable,  which 
makes  no  attempt  to  exclude  human  causality  either  by 
means  of  a  connected  system  of  nature  or  by  fate,  but  seeks 
to  clothe  itself  in  a  higher  form,  a  form  which  is  able  to  meet 
the  last  objections  advanced  by  indeterminism. 


260         §  28.   FREEDOM.       SECOND  FOEM  OF  THE  ANTITHESIS. 


§  28.  {Continuation) 

2].— THE  SECOND  FORM  OF  THE  ANTITHESIS.  PSYCHICAL 
DETERMINISM  AND  THE  INDETERMINISM  OF  INDIF- 
FERENCE. 

I.    PSYCHICAL  DETERMINISM. 

As  it  is  not  by  mere  mechanical  impulses  that  man  is 
moved,  or,  as  it  were,  driven,  so  too  in  what  he  is  and  does  he 
is  not  dependent  upon  the  caprices  or  irrational  chance  of  a 
fate,  which  impels  liim  now  in  one  direction  and  then  perhaps 
in  the  opposite  direction.  He  is  rather — says  determinism  of 
this  new  and  more  refined  form — relatively  free  over  against 
mundane  forces,  he  has  a  causal  energy  of  his  own,  and  can 
work  upon  them  and  resist  them.  Indeed,  the  higher  form  of 
determinism  lays  stress  upon  the  fact  that  man  has  a  causal 
power  of  a  constant,  determinate  kind,  according  to  the 
quantity  and  quality  of  the  energy  which  dwells  within  him. 
It  must  be  possible — it  says — for  the  will  to  be  an  actual 
determinate  will,  and  yet  to  be  free.  What  is  definite  or 
determined  cannot  be  inimical  to  freedom.  A  really  free 
character  must  also  be  a  character  specifically  determined. 
But — it  now  continues — the  will  acts  like  all  other  forces ; 
man  chooses,  decides,  acts  as  a  spiritual  force  in  accordance 
with  his  essential  nature,  his  psychical  constitution.  It  is  true 
that  man  with  his  receptivity  and  power  of  willing  is  not 
confined  to  a  narrow  range  of  things,  like  merely  natural 
beings.  Human  nature  is  universal,  and  can  therefore  will  an 
infinite  variety  of  things.  But  in  every  individual,  and  at 
every  moment,  the  choice  which  is  made  depends  upon  his 
whole  previous  disposition,  and  especially  upon  the  state  and 
bent  of  his  psychical  powers.  Neither  fate  nor  the  constitution 
of  external  nature  rules  him  from  without.  But  the  con- 
stitution of  his  nature  as  a  whole,  of  his  intellect  and 
inclinations,  all  that  he  brings  with  him  into  the  world  or 
that  he  has  acquired  through  culture,  this  it  is  which 
determines  his  will.  And  even  moral  impulses  may  arise 
from  the  habitual  character  thus  formed.  Man's  energies  and 
impulses  have  all  a  determining  influence  upon  him.  He  is 
himself  only  their  expression  and  executor  ;  and  thus  every- 


PSYCHICAL  DETERMINISM.  2  G  1 

thing  runs  its  naturally  determined  course,  although  the 
determination  is  of  a  psycliical  and  not  of  a  physico-mechanical 
kind.  It  is  denied  that  there  is  in  man  a  causal  source  of 
action,  belonging  to  himself  and  independent  of  psychical 
determination.  Freedom  is  denied  as  the  ability  to  set  in 
motion  a  new  series  of  actions  ;  consequently  it  is  denied  to 
be  the  cause  of  man's  power  to  originate  action  ;  or  in  other 
words,  it  is  denied  that  man  is  a  causality  in  the  higher  sense 
of  not  only  willing,  but  freely  willing  his  volition.  For  it  is 
held  rather  that  the  reason  why  man  is  and  becomes  a  cause 
lies  in  the  given  psychical  constitution  of  his  nature.  There 
is  no  such  thing  as  a  power  of  self-determination  with  respect 
to  the  inner  source  of  action. 

Thus  the  whole  chain  of  actions  and  habits  which  makes 
np  the  life  of  man  would  be  preformed  from  the  very  first, 
and  the  chain  would  unwind  itself — although  under  the 
co-operation  of  external  factors — just  as  leaves,  blossom,  and 
fruit  are  developed  from  a  seed  from  the  beginning  onward. 
And  this  necessity  from  first  to  last  would  lie  upon  the 
M'icked  in  their  wickedness  as  well  as  upon  the  good  in  their 
goodness.  They  would  have  morally  opposite  dispositions  ;  tlie 
one  would  be  created  for  evil,  the  other  for  good. 

But  indeterminism  now  refuses,  and  with  justice,  to  assent 
to  this  view.  It  now  admits,  indeed,  that  freedom  must  be 
able  to  will  something  definite  without  self-loss  accruing, 
and  even  that  decision,  determinateness,  is  a  necessary 
characteristic  of  freedom.  But  nevertheless  it  objects  to 
psychical  determinism  that  the  latter  fails  to  explain  the 
psychological  phenomena  of  shame,  penitence,  and  especially 
of  the  sense  of  guilt,  all  of  which  point  to  moral  freedom,  and 
that  it  rather  abolishes  imputation  and  guilt  altogether,  since 
it  denies  the  formal  element  of  free-will.  And  it  is  further 
objected  by  indeterminism,  that  on  this  view  the  contents  of 
an  act  of  will  can  no  longer  be  regarded  as  moral,  but  that 
since  determination  is  conceived  of  after  the  manner  of 
physical  and  not  of  ethical  laws,  these  contents  must  remain 
morally  indifferent  or  worthless.  Determinism  no  doubt  may 
reply — there  is  guilt  wherever  there  is  actual  causation ;  for 
example,  we  say  that  bad  weather  is  guilty  of  the  failure  of 
the  crops.      But  indeterminism  can  justly  retort — this  is  only 


262        §  28.    FREEDOM.       SECOND  FOEM  OF  THE  ANTITHESIS. 

physical  and  logical  imputation,  the  reference  of  a  result  to 
the  nearest  causality,  and  the  latter  may  itself  have  something 
else  as  its  cause,  behind  or  above  itself.  In  moral  imputation, 
on  the  other  hand,  and  in  the  strict  idea  of  guilt,  nothing  of 
the  kind  is  involved ;  but,  on  the  contrary,  it  is  implied  that 
there  is  no  determining  power  alien  to  man  which  makes  him 
the  cause  of  what  he  does ;  that  he  himself  is  responsible,  is 
the  alrla  or  reason  of  his  will  becoming  a  causal  power.  In 
short,  moral  guilt  and  imputation  have  only  a  footing  where 
man  is  conceived  as  a  causality  of  a  higher  kind  than  merely 
natural  causes,  where  he  is  thought  of  as  a  causality  in  the  second 
degree,  as  the  ultimate  ground — not  indeed  of  his  essential  being, 
but  nevertheless — of  his  acting  as  a  cause ;  in  other  words,  as 
having  the  power  to  make  himself  the  cause  of  an  act  or  not. 
Further,  indeterminism  can  justly  confront  determinism 
with  its  inability  to  assign  any  reason  why  some  should  be 
good  and  others  evil,  while  morality  nevertheless  makes  an 
unconditional  claim  upon  all  men,  through  the  essential  con- 
stitution of  human  nature.  If  the  distinction  between  good 
and  evil  is  absolute,  psychical  determinism  must  assume  that 
different  individuals  have  characters  of  an  absolutely  opposite 
kind.  But  in  that  case  men  no  longer  form  one  species  of 
being,  but  two  that  are  totally  different,  and  we  can  no  longer 
seriously  assert  that  morality  lays  an  unconditional  claim  upon 
all  men  alike.  Good  could  not  be  really  demanded  of  those 
who  are  psychically  predisposed  to  evil.  And  thus  from 
more  sides  than  one  psychical  determinism  would  prove  the 
ruin  of  the  ethical  idea.  Now,  should  determinism  take 
exception  to  this  inference,  on  the  ground  that  the  ethical  idea 
does  come  to  realization  in  what  is  good,  indeterminism  justly 
reminds  us,  that  if  human  action  is  necessitated  by  the  con- 
stitution of  man's  nature  and  the  disposition  originally  given 
him,  so  that  there  is  no  possibility  of  his  acting  otherwise 
than  he  does,  then  we  cannot  ascribe  to  him  any  real  share  of 
his  ovm  in  the  formation  of  his  moral  character,  and  thus  even 
the  good  as  viewed  from  the  standpoint  of  determinism  would 
contain  no  moral  element  properly  so  called.  Moreover, 
psychical  determinism  is  not  altogether  free  of  fatalism.  For 
if  everything  be — even  psychically — determined,  the  ques- 
tion arises,  what  is  the  determining  power  ?     It  cannot  be  a 


INDETEEMINISM  OF  INDIFfEEENCE.  263 

good  being  over  all,  for  lie  would  not  determine  men  to  what 
is  evil  as  well  as  to  what  is  good.  Fate  must  therefore  be 
posited  as  the  supreme  determining  power,  a  fate  to  which  the 
distinction  between  good  and  evil  is  indifferent,  and  which 
determines  men  aimlessly  and  blindly.  And  although  fate, 
when  looked  at  from  without,  is  irresistible  compulsion,  the 
principle  of  iron  necessity,  still,  inwardly  regarded,  it  is  in 
itself  without  goal  and  aim,  it  has  no  purpose  of  its  own,  but 
is  hollow  and  empty.  From  an  absolute  point  of  view,  there 
is  no  reason  why  it  should  determine  some  particular  thing 
rather  than  the  opposite ;  that  is  to  say,  fate  regarded  in- 
wardly is  absolute  chance. 

ir.    THE  INDETERMI'NISM  OF  INDIFFERENCE. 

2.  It  must  be  admitted  that  the  objections  advanced  by 
determinism  against  indeterminism  in  its  absolute  form  have 
not  been  removed.  jSTow,  when  indeterminism  acknowledges 
their  justice,  more  particularly  when  it  recognises  that  the 
idea  of  freedom  must  involve  not  a  bare  capacity,  an  impotent 
potency,  but  something  actual,  or  that  freedom  must  appro- 
priate to  itself  contents  of  a  detinite  kind,  then  indeter- 
minism also  reaches  a  higher  stage.  It  now  says :  the 
cause  of  moral  character  must  be  in  man  himself;  it  lies  in 
the  ability  to  choose  freely  between  one  kind  of  contents  and 
another;  more  particularly,  in  the  capacity  he  has  of  giving 
the  preference  to  good  or  to  evil,  without  losing  his  freedom. 
After  a  choice  has  been  made,  freedom  remains,  without  altera- 
tion or  self-loss,  the  same  that  it  was  before ;  it  is  the  faculty 
of  choice  pure  and  simple,  which  cannot  be  lost,  and  which 
always  retains  the  power  of  making,  just  as  readily,  an 
opposite  choice  to  the  one  it  actually  does  make.  By 
exercising  its  power  of  determination,  it  can  of  course  limit 
itself  for  the  moment  to  particular  contents.  But  this  only 
touches  the  surface  of  its  nature  ;  in  its  essence  the  faculty  of 
choice  remains  ever  the  same,  and  maintains  the  same  atti- 
tude of  indifference  towards  all  kinds  of  contents ;  it  is  the 
power  of  choice,  the  will  making  a  selection  and  nothing  more, 
or  in  other  words,  arbitrariness.  Hence  freedom  in  this  sense 
goes  by  the  name  liherum  arMtriuni  indiffer entice. 


264         §  28.    FREEDOM.       SECOND  FOEM  OF  THE  ANTITHESIS. 

This  idea  of  freedom  is  very  common ;  many  still  hold  that 
the  special  dignity  of  man  consists  in  his  power  of  arbitrary 
choice,  a  choice  in  which  the  contents  are  a  matter  of  indiffer- 
ence. But  against  this  conception  of  freedom  also,  many 
important  considerations  suggest  themselves,  some  of  which  are 
urged  with  much  force  from  the  side  of  determinism.  If  the 
essential  nature  of  freedom  be  exhaustively  described  in 
saying  that  it  consists  in  the  power  of  choice,  then  freedom 
must  be  incapable  of  growth;  just  as  little  can  it  be  diminished  ; 
hence  it  can  only  exist  in  its  entirety  or  not  at  all,  and  must 
consequently  be  complete  from  the  very  beginning.  But  such 
a  freedom  would  be  an  altogether  abnormal  phenomenon  in 
a  world  where  everything  is  passing  through  a  process  of 
growth.  Further,  if  freedom  were  no  more  than  the  liherioii 
arbitrium  indiffer entice,  and  were  nevertheless  an  abiding  attri- 
bute of  man,  it  would  be  impossible  for  any  definite  impression 
which  he  receives,  even  though  it  should  be  mediated  through 
his  own  will,  to  become  a  lasting  element  in  his  character. 
For  since  freedom,  considered  as  the  bare  freedom  of  choice^ 
can  admit  of  no  such  thing  as  determination,  without  ceasing 
to  be  in  itself  indifferent  to  all  contents  that  would  give  it  a 
permanent  character,  it  follows  that  man  would  have  the 
power,  after  performing  a  series  of  acts,  to  obliterate  their 
effects  at  any  moment.  But  experience  shows  that  the 
opposite  of  this  is  the  case.  The  actions  of  men  leave  traces 
behind  them,  they  produce  dispositions  which  exert  an  influence 
upon  the  whole  future  life.  By  this  means  freedom,  as  mere 
freedom  of  choice,  is  limited.  And  we  must  not  regard  this- 
as  implying  a  loss  of  freedom  ;  on  the  contrary,  man's  freedom 
would  give  him  no  real  power  over  himself,  did  its  exercise 
not  effect  something  permanent.  And  more  than  this,. 
moralitij  itself  would  suffer  through  such  a  conception  of 
freedom.  If  the  latter  were  absolutely  nothing  more  than  the 
power  of  choice,  it  would  have  to  remain  suspended,  in  com- 
plete indifference,  over  the  object  that  is  chosen  ;  it  could  only 
graze  it,  as  it  were,  it  could  never  unite  itself  to  anything 
firmly  and  reliably.  If  the  will  were  merely  an  agile  faculty, 
which  could  adopt  some  particular  form  of  contents  and 
then  just  as  readily  shake  itself  free  again,  what  advantage 
would  there  be  in  that  ?     How  could  a  character  grow  up  if 


INDETERMINISM  OF  INDIFFERENCE.  265 

the  self-determinations  of  man  could  not,  when  his  act  is  past, 
continue  to  work  on  within  him,  if  they  could  not  make  a 
lasting  impression  upon  him  ?  In  that  case  there  could  never 
be  any  progress,  man  would  continually  have  to  begin  from 
the  beginning  over  again.  Further,  if  the  special  dignity  of 
man,  the  divine  image,  is  to  be  seen  in  such  a  freedom,  in 
this  power  of  arbitrary  choice,  this  freedom  of  indifference — 
then  the  question  arises,  Is  God  not  to  be  regarded  as  free  ? 
He  cannot  enjoy  such  a  freedom  as  this,  which  is  simply 
arbitrariness,  since  He  is  not  mere  power ;  this  physical 
category  is  too  low  for  Him,  and  His  power,  on  the  contrary, 
is  subordinate  to  His  ethical  nature.  If  it  cannot  be 
accounted  as  belonging  to  the  freedom  of  God  to  be  able  to 
will  what  is  evil  as  well  as  what  is  good,  then  the  ideal  of 
man,  as  a  being  created  in  the  image  of  God,  must  lie  some- 
where else  than  in  a  merely  external,  ostensibly  free  but  in 
reality  adventitious,  relation  to  the  good. 

Finally,  the  doctrine  of  indiff"erence  would  also  come  into 
collision  with  the  moral  law.  The  latter  demands  that  we 
will  the  good  because  it  is  morally  necessary.  An  act  in 
which  we  did  what  was  good  merely  from  arbitrary  self-will 
or  caprice,  would  be  to  trifle  with  the  good,  w^ould  profane  it 
instead  of  rendering  it  homage.  If  man  in  himself  and  from 
the  whole  constitution  of  his  nature  were  indifferent  as  to  the 
contents  of  his  self-determination,  and  therefore  indiff'erent 
both  to  good  and  evil ;  further,  if  his  will,  from  its  essential 
nature,  held  the  same  relation  to  good  that  it  did  to  evil, — 
then  the  law  would  have  no  essential  connection  with  him, 
and  could  no  longer  be  absolutely  binding  upon  him.  Such 
a  boundless  right  of  self  -  determination,  moreover,  would 
abolish  man's  essential  determination  for  the  good.  Freedom 
can  only  be  given  us  for  the  sake  of  the  good ;  it  is  wholly 
inconceivable  that  a  force  should  be  admitted  into  the  world 
which  could  never  be  anything  else  but  mere  arbitrariness,  a 
force  which  could  never  afford  the  means  of  forming  a  good 
character,  or  even  of  performing  a  single  good  deed,  but  which 
would  rather  be  the  cause  of  endless  confusion  in  God's  world. 
Nor  is  it  the  case  either,  that  it  is  indifferent  to  freedom 
whether  it  surrender  itself  to  good  or  evil.  It  does  not  feel 
equally  healthy  or  vigorous  in  both  of  them  alike.      On  the 


266      §  2[».  fi;eedom.     third  form  of  the  antithesis. 

contrary,  when  it  chooses  evil  it  falls  into  contradiction  with 
itself  and  languishes ;  it  comes  under  the  power  of  the  natural, 
of  irrational  impulses,  and  sells  itself  into  the  kingdom  of 
bondage,  to  what  Paul  calls  alxy^cCKwala.  On  the  other  hand, 
it  is  only  when  it  chooses  the  good  that  it  reaches  complete 
harmony  with  its  idea ;  it  then  rises  out  of  the  bare  possibihty 
of  formal  freedom  into  true  and  real  freedom.  In  addition  to 
all  this,  the  theory  of  the  indifference  of  freedom  would  have 
to  assume  that  every  individual  is  born  in  a  state  of  entire 
moral  indetermination,  as  a  tabula  rasa,  whereas  experience 
and  Scripture  alike  recognise  that  every  one  has  a  natural 
tendency  towards  evil. 

The  controversy  between  these  two  opposing  theories  must 
convince  their  supporters  that  they  are  alike  untenable  in  their 
second  form  also,  and  that  another  and  a  higher  form  must  be 
sought  for  both. 


§  29.   (Continuation^ 

C— THIRD  FORM  OF  THE  ANTITHESIS.  THEOLOGICAL  PREDE- 
TERMINISM,  OR  THE  DOCTRINE  OF  ABSOLUTE  PREDESTI- 
NATION ;i  AND  THE  PREDETERMINISM  OF  FREEDOM,  OR 
FREEDOM  AS  TRANSCENDENTAL,  AS  BELONGING  TO  THE 
WORLD  OF  INTELLIGIBLE  BEING. 

T.    THEOLOGICAL  PREDETERMINISM,  OR  PREDESTINATION  AS  THE 
HIGHEST  FORM  OF  DETERJIINISM. 

Determinism  in  its  highest  form  admits  the  strength  of  the 
arguments  brought  against  psychical  determinism  and  attempts 
to  remedy  the  imperfections  of  the  latter  by  going  back  for 
the  ultimate  source  of  determination,  not  to  a  blind  cause 
such  as  objective  chance  or  fate,  nor  to  any  mere  natural 
force  even  of  a  spiritual  kind,  but  to  the  free,  living  God  of 
Providence,  who  is  guiding  the  world  to  a  good  end.  It  is 
now  said  that  this  free,  all-determining  will  of  God  is  even 
the  ground  of  a  possible  change  in  man,  of  a  conversion  from 
evil  to  good,  such  as  strict  psychical  determinism  cannot  admit. 
Hence  determinism  in  its  theological  form  can  now  deny,  as 
well   as  indeterminism,  that  evil  belongs  necessarily  to  the 

'  Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  iv.  §  130  (ii.  §  74,  75). 


PEEDESTINATIOX.       AUGUSTINE.  267 

psychical  nature  of  any  huma^n  being.  It  can  also  assert  the 
unity  of  the  human  race  and  its  universal  adaptation  for 
morality,  since  it  holds  that  all  men,  although  they  are  sinful, 
are  still  capable  of  being  acted  upon  by  God,  and  therefore, 
that  through  the  operation  of  a  supernatural,  creative  energy 
they  may  make  a  new  beginning  of  moral  life.  Theological 
determinism  has  appeared  in  three  forms  :  the  Infralapsari- 
anism  of  Augustine,  the  Sujyralapsa^nanism  of  Calvin  and 
Beza,  and  a  third  form  in  which  it  was  held  by  Schleiermacher. 
These  all  start  from  the  fact  of  universal  sinfulness,  of  man's 
need  of  as  well  as  his  capacity  for  redemption,  but  they  make 
the  final  character  and  fate  of  all  to  be  determined  solely  and 
simply  by  God. 

According  to  Augustine,  God  graciously  bestows  on  a  part 
of  mankind  tlie  power  of  fulfilling  the  law,  which  is  valid  for 
all ;  the  rest  He  passes  by  in  this  election,  leaving  them  in 
sin,  which  leads  to  their  damnation,  although  all  were  alike 
capable  of  receiving  His  grace.  In  this  way  the  distinction 
between  good  and  evil  is  explained  by  means  of  an  act  of 
election  on  the  part  of  God,  without  assuming  that  in  the 
human  race,  as  it  now  is,  there  is  any  power  of  free  choice. 
But  in  order  to  prevent  the  guilt  of  evil  and  the  condemnation 
of  a  certain  number  of  individuals  from  being  due  to  God, 
Augustine  teaches  that  in  Adam  the  whole  human  race  was 
morally  free,  and  that  in  him  all  have  sinned,  so  that  no  wrong 
is  done  to  any  one  when  election  passes  him  over  and  he  is 
left  to  condemnation.  Here,  therefore,  determinism  takes  up 
into  itself  an  element  of  indeterminism,  a  pre-existent  act  of 
freedom  on  the  part  of  all  men  in  Adam,  whereby,  of  course, 
the  system  of  purely  theological  determinism  is  at  once 
shattered.  But  even  then  the  riddle  remains  unsolved,  how 
it  can  accord  with  God's  love  to  refuse  to  some  the  help 
without  which  they  must  continue  in  sin,  while  others  to 
whom  help  is  given  are  no  whit  better  than  they.  If  a  breach 
has  to  be  made  in  the  deterministic  system  by  going  back  to 
Adam  and  the  freedom  of  man  as  found  in  him,  why  should 
not  the  distinction  between  those  who  become  believers  and 
those  who  remain  unbelievers  be  explained  without  this 
reference  to  Adam  at  all,  by  holding  that  the  same  freedom 
which  he  possessed  is  enjoyed  by  every  individual.      Or  again, 


2G8  §  29.    FREEDOM.       CALVIN'.       BEZA. 

why  should  theological  predeterminism  not  he  carried  out  in 
earnest  ?     Why  should  Adam's  fall  be  an  exception  ? 

The  Siq^ralapsarianism  of  Calvin  and  Beza  seeks  to  carry 
out  theological  determinism  with  stricter  logical  consistency. 
It  ventures  to  assign  the  ground  vjIhj  some  are  passed  over  by 
divine  election.  According  to  it,  it  is  for  the  good  of  the 
world,  which  exists  for  the  glory  of  God,  that  He  should  not 
only  reveal  His  mercy  towards  some,  but  also  His  justice 
towards  others.  Hence,  besides  vessels  of  grace  and  mercy, 
there  must  also  be  vessels  of  dishonour.  Hence,  too,  it 
believes  that  it  can  disallow  any  freedom  in  the  fall  of  Adam 
and  of  the  race  in  him,  and  can  trace  back  this  fall  to  an 
omnipotent  ordinance  of  God,  which  by  this  means  pro- 
vided the  material  for  the  above-mentioned  twofold  display  of 
the  majesty  of  God,  in  the  contrasted  forms  of  mercy  and 
justice.  In  the  case  of  the  elect,  evil  is  ordained  merely  with 
reference  to  redemption.  But  this  lands  us  in  a  still  greater 
enigma.  How  can  a  revelation  of  justice  be  possible,  if  evil 
be  based  upon  an  omnipotent  divine  decree  ?  How  can  the 
righteous  God  punish  what  He  Himself  has  irresistibly 
ordained  ?  And  what  would  become  of  the  inner  connection 
between  justice  and  love,  were  God  to  divide  mankind  in  this 
dualistic  fashion  ?  Justice  and  love  would  be  dissociated  in 
God  also,  and  would  not  exist  in  the  divine  mind  in  inward 
unity,  since  He  would  not,  in  all  that  He  does,  be  at  once  just 
and  loving,  but  would  be  loving  to  the  good  and  just  to  the 
bad  alone. 

In  order  now  to  be  enabled  to  maintain  that  the  moral 
detci'mincdion  of  all  men  is  essentially  the  same,  and  that  love 
rides  in  all  that  God  docs,  Schleiermacher  has  brought  for- 
ward theological  determinism  in  a  third  and  more  i^rfcct  form. 
According  to  him,  absolute  divine  determination  prevails 
indeed  without  exception,  but  it  is  likewise  the  very  means 
])y  which  men  are  everywhere  and  M'ithout  exception  deter- 
mined for  the  good.  He  holds  that  the  Lutheran  Church  is 
right  in  teaching  that  grace  is  universal  and  offered  to  all, 
but  he  agrees  with  Calvin  in  maintaining  that  it  is  also 
absolutely  irresistible  and  constant.  Since  everything  is  pre- 
determined by  God,  Supralapsarianism  is  justified  in  asserting 
that   evil  has   also  been    ordained    by  Him.      Nevertheless, 


SCHLEIERMACHER.  269 

God  does  not  contradict  Himself  when  He  enjoins  what  is 
good  and  forbids  what  is  evil.  He  is  not  indifferent  to  the 
distinction  between  them.  For  although  evil  is  willed  by 
God  together  with  grace,  it  is  willed  merely  as  something 
that  is  transitory  and  destined  to  be  abolished.  It  is  simply 
the  natural  set  alongside  a  still  imiDerfect  sense  of  God,  and 
this  preponderance  or  excess  of  the  natural,  which  is  ordained 
as  the  initial  condition  of  man, — this  actual  disproportion 
between  the  natural  and  the  spiritual, — is  the  flesh.  In  itself, 
however,  or  dissociated  from  its  connection  with  the  spirit,  the 
natural  would  be  innocent.  At  the  same  time  man  is  a  real 
and  not  merely  an  apparent  causality,  and  hence  guilt  is 
rightly  imputed  to  him.  So,  too,  evil  is  avoidable,  although 
not  immediately,  in  the  case  of  every  man ;  for  all  are 
destined  for  perfection.  Evil  does  not  belong  to  the  essence 
or  the  idea  of  man ;  regarded  absolutely,  it  is  rather  some- 
thing that  is  eternally  condemned  and  avoidable — avoidable, 
that  is,  through  God's  grace,  which  in  every  age  comes  in  to 
strengthen  the  knowledge  of  God  which  man  has  attained. 
In  favour  of  this  theory  it  must  be  said  that  it  does  not,  like 
the  indeterminism  of  indifference,  conceive  of  freedom  as 
mere  caprice  or  as  a  given,  completed  whole,  but  as  capable 
of  growth,  Schleiermacher's  theory  also  recognises  the  fact 
that  man  is  not  born  empty  both  of  good  and  evil,  but  with 
a  preponderating  tendency  towards  evil. 

But  even  this  highest  form  of  determinism  is  exposed  to 
the  objection,  that  if  everything  be  effected  through  the 
irresistible  power  of  grace,  there  can  be  no  such  thing  as 
a  moral  process,  but  merely  something  that  is  essentially 
a  physical  operation.  The  world,  even  the  human  will, 
would  be  absorbed  in  the  will  of  God.  The  world  would 
be  no  more  than  a  manifestation  of  the  divine  will,  and 
would  consequently  have  only  a  docetic  existence.  In  the 
last  resort,  too,  this  form  of  determinism,  like  all  others, 
would  make  evil  the  result  of  an  omnipotent  decree  on  the 
part  of  God.  This  indeed  is  defended  on  the  ground  that 
God  wills  a  gradual  process  of  growth,  which  necessarily 
involves  imperfection  in  its  earlier  stages.  But  gradual 
growth  does  not  necessarily  include  evil.  Evil  is  a  deviation 
from  the  normal  movement  ;  when  it  exists,  there  must  be  a 


270    §  29.  FREEDOM.   PEEDETERMINISM  OF  FREEDOM. 

retrogression  from  the  way  that  has  been  entered  upon,  a 
return  to  the  right  way  of  gradual  growth  ;  the  latter  does 
not  admit  either  of  deviation  or  retrogression.  Finally, 
should  Schleiermacher  say  that  evil  is  indeed  a  discord  or 
disturbance,  but  that  it  is  ultimately  resolved  and  disappears, 
since  it  was  ordained  in  connection  with  redemption,  he 
brings  the  divine  will  into  contradiction  with  itself,  for  he 
makes  God  by  an  omnipotent  decree  ordain  something  which 
His  law  and  His  ethical  nature  alike  condemn. 

II.  THE  PREDETERMINISM  OF  FREEDOM. 

Accordingly,  indeterminism  does  not  surrender  to  this  last 
and  highest  form  of  determinism,  but  seeks  to  shape  itself  so 
as  to  be  able  to  def}'  the  weighty  objections  which  deter- 
minism has  advanced  {£.  ii.).  It  now  concedes,  not  only  that 
freedom  must  not  be  sought  for  in  mere  arbitrariness,  and 
must  not  exclude  permanent  characterization,  but  also  that  it 
does  not  exist  ready-made  from  the  very  first  or  by  nature, 
but  is  formed  and  fashioned  by  human  action.  It  also  con- 
cedes that  freedom  has  an  essential  relation  to  the  law,  and 
consequently  destroys  itself  when  exercised  arbitrarily ;  and 
that,  on  the  contrary,  it  gains  in  strength  when  it  unites  itself 
to  what  is  morally  necessary.  On  the  other  side,  indeter- 
minism still  maintains  inflexibly  that  the  moral  condition  of 
man  must  be  due  to  an  act  of  his  own,  that  the  entire  con- 
stitution of  his  moral  nature  must  have  its  ground  in  a  free 
act  of  self-determination  on  the  part  of  man,  and  not  in  any 
mechanical,  psychical,  or  theological  determination.  Eacli 
one  gives  himself  his  own  peculiar  character.  Indeterminism 
is  now  confronted  with  the  following  problem.  It  sees — 
what  is  evident  on  the  face  of  things — that  man  is  never  a 
mere  tabula  rasa,  but  at  every  moment  has  a  determinate 
character ;  more  particularly,  it  sees  that  in  human  life  an 
egoistic  bias  early  makes  its  appearance,  a  tendency  which  cannot 
be  derived  from  a  fall,  taking  place  in  the  empirical  earthly 
life  of  each  individual.  Accordingly,  to  maintain  its  own 
point  of  view,  and  to  explain  the  determination  that  so  mani- 
festly exists  in  the  present  actual  world,  indeterminism  falls 
back  upon  a  free  act  or  free  acts  of  man  in  an  intelligible 


KANT.       SCHELLING.  271 

world  ;  and  this  logically  leads  to  a  super-temporal  or  pre- 
temporal  mode  of  existence,  or  in  other  words,  to  the  doctrine 
of  pre  -  existence.  In  this  intelligible  region,  it  is  held, 
freedom  makes  its  decision  by  an  act  which  gives  to  man 
the  specific  character  that  we  see  he  possesses  empirically, 
or  on  earth.  This  theory  is  held,  in  difierent  ways,  by  Kant, 
Schelling,  Origen,  and  Jul.  Mliller. 

According  to  Kant,  the  visible  sensible  world  is  absolutely 
under  the  sway  of  the  law  of  necessity.  But  the  spirit  has 
within  itself  an  intelligible  region,  a  kingdom  of  freedom  in 
which  it  determines  itself,  above  or,  as  it  were,  behind  time. 
Since  time  has  for  Kant  only  subjective  significance,  he  can 
conceive  of  this  act  of  self-determination,  which  takes  place  in 
eternity,  as  constantly  pervading  and  operative  in  the  life 
of  man.  But  if  the  whole  external  world  and  the  empirical 
human  life  remain  subject  to  the  law  of  necessity,  while 
freedom  is  adjudged  to  belong  to  purely  intelligible  being, 
then  freedom  is  made  utterly  powerless,  and  morality  is  con- 
demned to  a  merely  incorporeal,  spiritualistic  existence. 
Moreover,  when  Kant  derives  the  sinful  bias  with  which 
we  are  born  from  an  act  of  freedom,  he  thereby  admits  a 
connection  between  the  intelligible  and  the  empirical  world, 
and  thus  introduces  an  inconsistency  into  his  system.  And  a 
similar  remark  may  be  made  when  he  asserts  the  possibility 
of  a  change  in  the  intelligible  character.  For  he  thereby 
admits  that  history  and  therefore  time  has  objective  signi- 
ficance. 

According  to  Schelling,  every  man  has  fixed  his  own 
specific  character  by  a  pre-temporal  and  super-temporal  act 
of  freedom,  and  enters  upon  his  life  in  time  with  the  deter- 
minate qualities  he  has  thus  given  himself,  so  that  all  he 
does  in  the  world  is  to  live  out  this  indwelling  character. 
Thus  the  whole  earthly  life  is  held  to  be  delivered  over 
irrevocably  to  determinism.  But  if  man  had  absolutely  no 
power  to  begin  a  new  series  of  actions  from  M'ithin  outwards, 
he  could  no  longer  effect  any  moral  change — either  for  good 
or  evil — in  his  own  earthly  life.  And  thus  there  would  be 
two  classes  of  men  eternally  distinct,  and  the  whole  earthly 
life  would  be  without  real,  intrinsic  value.  One  act  alone 
in   man's  whole    existence  would   have  moral  worth,  and  it 


272  §  29.    FREEDOM.       ORIGEN.       MULLER. 

would  lie  outside  consciousness  altogether.  History  would 
only  have  the  semblance  of  significance.  For  man,  in  his 
time-life,  instead  of  making  some  moral  acquisition,  could  do 
no  more  than  show  or  reveal  what  had  been  already  implanted 
within  him  through  his  pre-existent  act  of  freedom. 

In  reply  to  this  it  may  be  said,  with  Origen  and  Julius 
Mliller,  that  the  pre-existent  act  referred  to  does  not  deter- 
mine freedom  wholly  and  for  ever ;  that,  on  the  contrary, 
conversion,  for  example,  always  remains  possible  to  man,  and 
that  freedom  therefore  continues  to  exist  alongside  of  deter- 
mination or  necessity.  This,  however,  is  a  virtual  admission 
that  no  firm  standing  ground  is  afforded  either  by  pure 
indeterminism  or  determinism.  According  to  Origen,  the 
souls  of  men  have,  as  a  punishment,  been  clothed  with 
bodies,  and  sent  to  earth  as  to  a  prison.  Jul.  Mliller 
dissents  from  this  view,  since  it  gives  to  the  body  an 
altogether  accidental  connection  with  the  soul.  He  holds, 
on  the  contrary,  that  even  apart  from  the  fall  altogether, 
human  souls  would  have  been  destined  to  be  united  to  a 
body  for  a  time  ;  and  thus,  according  to  him,  men  were  at 
first  created  incomplete.  But  in  that  case  it  is  all  the  more 
surprising  that  the  human  soul  should  be  created  so  perfect 
as  to  be  able  to  undertake,  in  its  pre-existent  condition,  an 
act  of  such  infinite  consequence  and  so  pregnant  with  fate. 
He  fails  to  show  how  souls  in  the  pre-existent,  intelligible 
state,  with  no  bodies  and  no  consciousness  of  a  world,  could 
ever  perform  an  act  of  this  kind,  which  presupposes  the  ex- 
istence of  a  high  degree  of  freedom  and  self-consciousness, 
such  as  they  could  not  possibly  possess  at  their  creation. 
Further,  if  we  cannot  go  back  to  the  idea  of  indifference  as 
affording  an  exhaustive  definition  of  freedom,  what  is  required 
is,  to  show  how  the  element  of  truth  contained  in  determinism 
is  to  be  incorporated  with  the  idea  of  freedom,  and  how  the 
latter  is  to  be  defined  so  as  to  do  full  justice  to  it. 

If  we  now  survey  the  two  sets  of  theories  which  we  have 
discussed,  the  result  is  as  follows.  The  whole  truth  has  not 
yet  been  found  even  in  the  third  form  either  of  determinism 
or  indeterminism,  although  both  of  these  have  caught  up 
elements  of  it  into  themselves,  elements  which  belong 
originally  to  the  other  member  of  the  antithesis.       Never- 


§  30.    POSITIVE  DOCTRINE  OF  FREEDOM.  273 

theless,  the  dialectical  necessity  of  the  matter  in  hand  com- 
pels us  to  recognise  that  we  must  seek  for  a  union  of  the 
two  factors  of  necessity  and  freedom,  and  by  this  means  raise 
the  idea  of  freedom  above  bare  indeterminism  on  the  one  side 
and  bare  determinism  on  the  other. 


§  30.  Positive  Doctrine  of  Freedom. 

The  full  idea  of  freedom  can  only  be  realized  and  can  only  be 
apprehended  in  a  plurality  of  stages,  which  it  must  pass 
through  in  the  course  of  an  actual  moral  process.  Such 
a  process  is  recognised  neither  by  pure  Determinism  nor 
by  pure  Indeterminism  ;  it  is  set  in  motion,  on  the  one 
side  by  the  opposition,  on  tlie  other  side  by  the  intimate 
connection  between  the  two  factors  of  Freedom  and 
Necessity.  The  first  stage  is  that  of  freedom  in  essence,. 
or  essential  freedom  (cf,  §  24.  25.  1,  2,  19.  1-3), 
corresponding  to  conscience  at  its  earliest  stage.  It 
is  only  when  the  law  becomes  revealed  in  conscience- 
(§  25.  2)  that  the  faculty  of  moral  choice,  which  lies  hid 
in  this  rudimentary  form  of  freedom,  is  brought  out  into 
actual  exercise ;  and  then  the  second  stage  has  been  reached. 
Here  a  double  possibility  is  set  before  man.  He  can 
suffer  himself  to  be  determined  either  by  the  good  or 
by  its  opposite  ;  and  therein  he  possesses  freedom,  as 
the  power  of  choice  between  good  and  evil.  But  the 
ability  to  make  a  choice  is  not  yet  true  freedom  ;  it 
simply  marks  the  stage  of  formed  or  sid^jcctive  freedom, 
and  this  can  only  be  a  transitional  stage.  The  third' 
stage  and  the  full  idea  of  freedom  is  only  reached  when 
man  no  longer  makes  a  mere  arbitrary  choice,  in- 
different to  what  is  morally  necessary,  but,  recognising 
the  good  to  be  the  true  essence  or  the  idea  of  his 
own  personality,  unites  himself  firmly  to  it,  and  thereby 
gives  himself  a  definite  moral  character,  so  that  through 
the  emancipating  power  of  love  to  and  delight  in  the 

s 


2 '74  §  30.    POSITIVE  DOCTEINE  OF  FREEDOM. 

good,  it  becomes  more  and  more  a  moral  impossibility 
for  him  to  choose  what  is  evil.  This  is  real  freedom — 
what  the  New  Testament  calls  the  glorious  liberty  of 
the  children  of  God  (so-called  theological  freedom).  In 
it  the  faculty  of  choice  is  still  preserved  ;  but  it  is  no 
longer  a  factor  operating  in  isolation  ;  on  the  contrary, 
it  is  taken  up  as  an  organic  element  into  the  will, 
now  indissolubly  united  to  the  good.  In  this  real 
freedom  essential  freedom  attains  to  pure  and  efficient 
realization. 

1.  Biblical  Doctrine. — Scripture  teaches  neither  absolute 
determinism  nor  an  empty  liberum  arbitrium  indifferens.  On 
the  contrary,  the  idea  of  essential  freedom  is  expressed  in  the 
phrase  "the  image  of  God"  (Gen.  i.  26,  27).  Man  was 
created  in  this  image  (iop^S).  The  essential  characteristic 
of  man  is,  that  he  is  destined  for  God.  But  this  his  desti- 
nation is  not  realized  at  once  and  without  mediation.  This 
truth  is  involved  in  the  words  which  tell  us  that  he  was 
created  for  likeness  to  God  (iniO"|3).  According  to  these 
words,  man  has  an  essential  relation  to  the  good  or  the  morally 
necessary ;  and  as  long  as  he  continues  to  be  at  one  with  the 
will  of  God,  he  is  also  in  a  happy  state  of  harmony  with  him- 
self, a  state  that  accords  with  his  true  nature  ;  although  it  is 
not  till  after  the  fall  that  he  has  a  living  experience  of  the 
fact.  The  power  of  moo-al  cJioice  is  then  called  into  play  by 
means  of  moral  commands.  These  commands  appear  indeed 
in  a  positive,  external  form,  and  their  inward  goodness  is 
not  at  first  recognised.  Still,  man  knows  that  it  is  his 
duty  to  exhibit  childlike  piety  and  obedience,  and  this 
makes  him  a  moral  being.  Accordingly,  his  consciousness 
of  the  law  is  gradually  developed  along  with  his  conscious- 
ness of  himself,  of  the  world  and  of  God,  is  strengthened 
by  the  moral  customs  of  the  patriarchal  age,  and  is  at  last 
fully  unfolded  in  a  national  form  in  the  law  of  Moses.  Even 
the  Mosaic  law  is  the  friend  of  freedom,  and  the  Hebrews  did 
not  fail  to  perceive  that  it  was  bound  up  with  the  very  being 
and  therefore  with  the  freedom  of  the  nation  (Deut.  xxx. 
15   f.;  Jer.  vi.    16,   xviii.    11  ;  Sir.  xv.   14  f).     Hence  the 


BIBLICAL  DOCTBINK  275 

high  praise  that  is  given  to  the  law  (Ps.  xxxii.,  ciii.,  cxix.).  It 
awakens  the  consciousness  of  freedom,  and  summons  man  to 
moral  effort.  According  to  Deut.  xxx.  15,  good  and  evil  are 
set  before  man  that  he  may  make  his  choice.  Christianity 
also  recognises  essential  freedom  (Eom.  vii.  22  ;  John  iii. 
20,  21),  and  likewise  freedom  of  choice  between  good  and 
evil  (Matt.  xxii.  2  f.,  xxiii.  37  ;  Acts  vii.  51  f.).  Still,  mere 
freedom  of  clioice  by  itself  does  not  receive  the  name  of  free- 
dom. 'Eicouatov  is  used  (Heb.  x.  26)  to  denote  man's 
spontaneity  when  it  takes  the  direction  of  evil.  It  is  self- 
evident,  however,  that  the  Old  and  New  Testaments  do  not 
stop  short  with  the  subjective  element  in  freedom ;  even 
leaving  the  effects  of  sin  out  of  account  altogether,  every 
good  gift  comes  from  God  the  Fatlier  of  lights,  who  must 
work  in  man  both  to  will  and  to  do  (James  i.  17  f. ; 
Phil.  ii.  13).  In  addition  to  this  also,  guilt  and  sin,  which 
are  imputed  to  man  because  of  his  freedom,  produce  a  con- 
dition of  bondage,  of  dominion  of  the  flesh,  and  at  the  same 
time  of  fear  and  timidity  before  God.  Even  in  Old  Testa- 
ment times  this  was  perceived  by  the  prophets,  and  hence 
they  deemed  a  new  covenant  necessary  (Jer.  xxxi.  ;  Ezek. 
xi.  19).  Then  the  Son  came,  in  order  that  from  being  bonds- 
men we  might  become  free  children  of  God  (John  viii.  31,  32  ; 
Piom.  vi.  15  f.,  viii.  17  ff.).  The  divine  agency  that  now  comes 
into  play  has  the  power  to  determine  man  ;  but  the  determina- 
tion which  is  given  is  wholly  favourable  to  freedom,  and 
James  plainly  says  (i.  25)  that  Christianity  is  the  vofioq 
reXeio?  t?^<?  ekev6€p[a<i.  According  to  the  New  Testament, 
true  freedom  is  to  be  found  in  the  realization  of  the  new 
man,  made  in  the  image  of  God  (Rom.  viii.  2 1  ;  2  Cor.  iii.  1 7  ; 
Eph.  iv.  23  f.;  Col.  iii.  9  f. ;  1  Pet.  ii.  16).  There  is  no 
word  in  the  New  Testament  of  freedom  apart  from  Christ ; 
on  the  contrary,  Christ  says,  Without  me  ye  can  do  nothing 
(John  XV.  5). 

2.  Possibility  and  necessity  of  the  facnliy  of  moral  choice. — 
It  is  true  that  the  Eeformers  Luther  and  Calvin  believed  that 
they  must  deny  man's  freedom  of  moral  choice,  not  only  on 
account  of  original  sin  and  with  reference  to  the  liberum 
arhitrium  in  spiritualihis,  but  also  in  order  to  maintain  the 
divine  omnipotence.      They  were  led  to  this  view  hj  their 


276    §  30.    POSITIVE  DOCTRINE  OF  FREEDOM.       POSSIBILITY  AND 

opposition  to  Pelagianism.  But  the  German  Evangelical 
Church,  following  Melanchthon  in  this  respect,  has  always 
sought  to  leave  room  for  moral  freedom  of  choice,  and  has 
refused  to  acknowledge  the  grounds  on  which  its  possibility 
is  denied.  And  in  fact,  when  it  is  said  that  God  has 
created  free  beings,  no  limitation  of  His  omnipotence  is 
implied,  since  the  idea  of  omnipotence  simply  describes  His 
absolute  power,  but  says  nothing  as  to  how  it  is  exercised. 
God  is  indeed  at  every  moment  the  sole  ground  of  the  being 
of  His  creatures.  But  if  nothing  higher  could  exist  than 
creatures  at  the  level  of  nature,  that  is  to  say,  if  there  could 
not  be  free  spirits,  then  the  creative  omnipotence  of  God 
could  not  become  a  cause  in  the  full  sense  of  the  term. 
A  causal  power  has  not  operated  in  the  highest  sense,  and 
has  not  advanced  beyond  the  relations  of  identity  and  sub- 
stantiality, until  it  has  produced  something  which  does  not 
remain  absorbed  in  it,  and  in  utter  and  helpless  dependence 
upon  it,  but  which  has  an  existence  by  itself  and  leads  an 
independent  life.  Now  in  nature  the  divine  causality  does 
not  reach  this  form  ;  there  life  and  its  movements  are  every- 
where determined  by  the  will  of  God,  and  are  the  expression 
of  that  will.  Accordingly,  the  creative  causality  of  God  does 
not  manifest  itself  fully  in  nature :  it  can  only  do  so  when  it 
calls  free  beings  into  existence.  Further,  the  necessity  for 
the  existence  of  free  beings  is  rendered  still  more  evident 
when  we  consider  not  only  the  creative  omnipotence  of 
God,  but  also  the  ethical  end  for  which  the  world  has 
been  created  by  an  ethical  God.  God's  omnipotence,  in 
accordance  with  His  purpose  of  love,  wills,  for  the  realization 
of  the  good,  free  and  essentially  self-determining  beings.  An 
obedience  towards  God  that  did  not  involve  a  capacity  to 
resist  His  will,  would  not  be  free  ;  man  would  remain  merely 
a  higher  kind  of  natural  being,  determined  throughout  by 
divine  omnipotence.  Also,  he  would  not  be  an  ultimate  end, 
for  whatever  lacks  independent  existence  can  be  no  more 
than  a  means.  But  God  wills  a  world  that  shall  be  of  worth 
in  itself,  that  shall  live  out  its  own  life  in  the  freedom  of 
love,  and  not  merely  attain  to  a  spectral  existence  over  against 
His  irresistible  sway.  It  is  indeed  a  great,  bold  thought, 
that  man  is  so  free  with  regard  to  God  that  he  can  withstand 


NECESSITY  OF  MOKAL  CHOICE.  277 

God.  But  all  the  while,  omnipotence  remains  as  the  power 
from  which  freedom  derives  its  existence  (Ps.  civ.  29).  Thus, 
then,  God  proves  Himself  to  be  a  loving  Father,  by  willing 
the  existence  of  free  children,  made  in  His  own  image,  with 
whom  He  can  enter  upon  a  free  interchange  of  love.  He 
wills  that  on  the  basis  of  the  nature  which  He  gave  to  man 
at  creation,  a  new  creation  should  now  be  built,  in  which 
a  free,  reciprocal  fellowship  of  love  can  be  formed  between 
God  and  man. 

K'ow  determinism  and  indeterminism  are  alike  in  this,  that 
on  their  showing  no  actual  moral  gain  is  ever  acquired  in 
human  life,  nothing  really  new  is  won  for  the  glory  of  God 
and  the  good  of  the  world.  For,  according  to  determinism, 
everything  is  given  and  complete  in  the  divine  decree  ;  the 
future — whether  it  be  good  or  evil — is  all  the  same  as  if  it 
were  already  present  or  past.  Man,  instead  of  being  engaged 
by  reason  of  his  freedom  in  the  work  of  building  up  a  second 
moral  world,  becomes  himself  a  mere  manifestation  of  the 
absolute  divine  decree,  in  the  web  of  which  no  distinct  threads 
■of  human  freedom  are  found.  On  the  other  hand,  indeter- 
minism possesses,  in  the  notion  of  freedom  which  it  advocates, 
a  principle  which  never  disentangles  itself  from  the  infinite, 
restless,  and  ever-shifting  power  of  choosing  an  opposite  course. 
But  in  this  way,  too,  nothing  fixed  and  permanent  would  ever 
be  reached,  as  absolute  motion  is  in  fact  nothing  but  rest. 
Freedom  can  make  real  progress,  and  can  therefore  arrive  at 
full  correspondence  with  its  idea,  only  when  a  good  and  per- 
manent specific  character  results  from  its  exercise,  only 
when  it  enters  into  such  a  connection  with  its  apparent 
opposite — necessity — and  submits  to  the  influence  of  the 
latter  in  such  a  way,  that  the  free  and  the  morally  neces- 
sary are  indissolubly  interwoven  with  each  other.  Or  to 
express  the  same  thing  in  other  words  :  indeterminism  and 
determinism,  which  claim  to  be  the  champions,  the  one  of 
freedom,  the  other  of  the  rights  of  the  good  on  its  divine 
side,  never  get  beyond  a  barren  fixity  or  stahilism, — in  the 
one  case  of  a  subjective,  in  the  other  of  an  objective  kind, — 
until  on  the  one  hand  determinism  conceives  of  the  divine 
decree  in  such  a  way  as  to  make  room  for  the  factor  of 
formal,  subjective  freedom ;   and  on  the  other,  indeterminism 


278  §  30.    POSITIVE  DOCTlilNE  OF  FEEEDOM. 

admits  a  process  in  which  freedom  is  lastingly  and  enduringly 
determined  by  what  is  morally  necessary. 

3.  Tlie  stages  in  the  realization  of  freedom. — The  process  in 
which  the  idea  of  freedom  differentiates  itself,  and  in  which  it 
at  the  same  time  comes  to  full  realization,  demands  (1)  a 
starting-point.  This  is  freedom  in  the  form  of  essential  free- 
dom. It  also  demands  (2)  mediation,  through  an  objective 
and  a  subjective  principle,  or  through  the  good,  as  objective 
and  divine,  offering  itself  to  man's  free  choice  and  decision  in 
order  to  make  him  the  subject  of  moral  determination.  Lastly, 
there  must  be  (3)  a  goal,  and  this  is  freedom  as  it  is  destined 
to  appear  in  the  final  result — viz.  as  the  union  of  the  free 
and  the  necessary. 

At  the  first  stage,  man  is  a  totality  in  which  necessity  and 
freedom  are  as  yet  directly  blended  with  each  other,  although 
the  bond  of  union  is  dissoluble.  Here  the  element  of  necessitj'' 
is  seen  in  the  absolute  dependence  of  man's  being  or  existence 
upon  God,  as  well  as  in  the  original  connection  of  his  nature 
with  the  good,  which,  by  reason  of  its  obligatory  power,  lays 
him  under  unconditional  claims.  This  connection  does  not 
act  upon  the  will  as  a  compulsory  force,  but  nevertheless  the 
effect  of  it  is  that  freedom  cannot  thrive  where  it  is  in  con- 
tradiction to  the  good.  In  addition  to  this,  man  is  influenced 
by  the  individuality  which  God  has  given  him,  as  well  as  by 
his  environment  and  the  natural  relations  which  he  holds  to 
other  human  beings.  Freedom,  on  the  other  hand,  is  hardly 
exercised  seriously  to  begin  with.  The  human  individual  is 
at  first  swayed  almost  entirely  by  objective  forces  or  natural 
impulses, — although  these  may  be  good,  as  for  example, 
natural  piety, — he  has  not  as  yet  got  the  mastery  of  himself, 
and  it  is  only  in  the  vaguest  sense  that  he  can  be  called  a 
responsible  being. 

But  such  a  simple,  immediate  union  of  the  free  and  the 
natural — a  union  which  may  not  be  compulsion  but  certainly 
is  not  freedom  —  cannot  be  the  final  condition  of  man 
(§  11,  19).  Each  of  these  two  factors  —  necessity  and 
freedom — must  appear  separately,  in  order  that  a  conscious 
union  of  them  may  be  effected  through  the  human  will.  This 
separation  is  brought  about  by  the  knowledge  of  the  moral 
law  or  of  the  morally  necessary.     The    faculty  of  choice  was 


STAGES  IN  THE  REALIZATION  OF  FREEDOM.  279 

exercised  at  first  upon  purely  finite  matters,  —  llheruni 
arhitrium  speciflcationis, — but  when  the  law  entered,  freedom 
was  challenged  and  drawn  forth  into  action.  When  freedom 
thus  appears  by  itself,  it  involves  the  possibility  of  arbitrary 
choice,  it  is  the  faculty  of  choosing  between  good  and  evil. 
By  means  of  the  law  there  is  opened  up  to  man  for  the  first 
time  a  serious  choice  between  two  worlds.  Everything  is  now 
made  to  hinge  upon  a  free  decision  of  infinite  worth  (Matt. 
xvi.  26).  Neither  of  these  worlds  acts  in  the  way  of  com- 
pulsion. The  agent  decides  to  which  of  the  two  he  will 
surrender  himself,  and  his  decision  depends  entirely  upon 
whether  he  wills  to  be  good  or  bad.  Of  this  decision  the  will 
is  the  ultimate  responsible  cause ;  we  must  not  seek  for 
another  cause  behind  the  will  and  necessitating  it,  for  the 
simple  reason  that  no  other  exists.  If  there  were  another,  we 
would  have  to  deny  moral  freedom,  and  would  again  be  landed 
in  pure  determinism. 

The  decision  which  man  makes  may  be  opposed  to  what  is 
morally  necessary,  and  may  therefore  be  arbitrary.  In  tlie 
latter  case  it  might  seem  as  if  he  were  enlarging  his  freedom ; 
but,  on  the  contrary,  he  falls  into  discord  with  himself  and 
his  moral  energy  is  weakened,  because  he  is  in  contradiction 
Willi  his  essential  freedom,  which  involves  the  essential 
determination  of  man  for  the  good.  When  man  turns 
arbitrarily  away  from  the  good,  instead  of  thereby  gaining 
greater  freedom,  he  comes,  as  has  been  shown  above,  into  a 
state  of  bondage  or  servitude  under  an  alien  power ;  even  his 
faculty  of  formal  self-determination  is  gradually  lost,  and  he 
yields  to  the  forces  of  nature  and  to  his  own  lower  impulsef^ 
and  egoistic  passions.  Such  a  moral  decision  too  is  irrational : 
while,  on  the  contrary,  man's  decision  for  the  good  is  rational 
and  not  arbitrary,  inasmuch  as — so  far  as  the  grounds  of 
determination  are  concerned — it  is  made  on  account  of  the 
goodness  of  the  good.  In  an  arbitrary  choice,  on  the  other 
hand,  man  sets  himself  in  opposition  to  the  good  from  a  false 
desire  for  freedom,  he  seeks  to  become  self-centred,  to  forget 
his  dependence  upon  God,  and  to  be  —  like  God  —  self- 
sufficing.  Man  is  indeed  essentially  destined  to  become  like 
unto  God,  but  the  evil-doer  perverts  this  by  seeking  to  be  a 
god  alongside  of  God.     But  since  God  alone  can  be  God,  and 


280  §  30.  POSITIVE  DOCTKINE  OF  FKEEDOM. 

can  endure  no  gods  beside  Himself,  this  false  direction  taken 
by  man  leads  to  an  endeavour  on  his  part  to  become  an 
opposing  deity, — an  act  of  unreason  of  which  the  other  side 
is,  that  man  now  falls  into  bondage  under  the  powers  of 
nature,  since  these  alone  can  furnish  the  human  will  with 
concrete  contents,  when  it  disdains  to  accept  the  divine  as  its 
contents.  Nevertheless,  it  is  necessary  even  to  the  good  that 
there  should  always  be  the  possibility  of  evil.  This  does  not 
merely  mean  that  the  will  in  itself  must  be  able  to  will  both 
good  and  evil,  but  that  the  possibility  of  evil  must  be 
definitely  present  in  thought.  For  the  good  must  be  chosen 
for  this  reason,  that  it  is  the  good  and  not  its  opposite; 
consequently  it  is  only  willed  as  such,  if  at  the  same  time  the 
conscious  exclusion  of  its  opposite  is  also  willed,  and  therefore 
if,  when  good  is  consciously  posited,  evil  is  likewise  posited  as 
a  possibility,  but  is  rejected. 

The  third  stage  is  that  in  which  freedom  surrenders  itself 
to  be  taken  possession  of  by  the  good,  to  be  constrained  by  its 
attractive  and  inspiring  power,  and  to  be  filled  with  desire  for 
and  love  towards  its  glorious  perfection  (as  manifested  in  a 
personal  and  living  form  in  Christ).  The  good  must  not  be 
a  mere  subjective  product ;  it  must  present  itself  to  man 
objectively,  since  his  autonomy  is  only  secondary.  It  must 
be  given,  first  of  all,  in  the  form  of  a  command  of  God,  the 
primal  Good,  as  something  which  He  wills.  Then,  too,  it  is 
God  alone  and  not  man  who  invests  the  good  with  its  beauty 
and  attractive  power.  All  that  man  can  do  is  to  suffer  him- 
self to  be  attracted  and  thus  determined  by  the  good.  Hence 
if  freedom  is  to  correspond  with  its  idea,  it  must  be  receptive 
towards  the  divine  will,  must  allow  itself  to  be  inspired  and 
determined  by  that  will  as  the  original  source  of  good.  Then 
only  does  it  act  in  conformity  with  its  creaturely  position. 
Pelagianism  and  Deism,  which  isolate  man  from  God  and  God 
from  man,  are  excluded.  The  fact,  too,  that  freedom  must 
assume  a  receptive  attitude  towards  the  divine,  in  order  to 
receive  its  proper  character,  forms  an  indissoluble  bond  of 
connection  between  religion  and  morality.  Man  does  not 
attain  to  full,  actual  freedom  until  he  yields  himself  up  to 
the  captivating,  overpowering  influence  of  divine  good, 
surrenders  himself  to  its  ideal  beauty,  as  revealed  in  all  its 


THEOLOGICAL  FKEEDOM.  281 

majesty  in  Christ,  and  allows  its  spirit  to  rule  within  him  as 
a  higher  power.  Then  the  will  is  no  longer  divided  against 
itself,  but  enjoys  a  higher  sense  of  freedom,  since  it  has  now 
found  and  allied  itself  with  its  own  true  and  proper  nature, 
which  henceforth  governs  it,  and  comes  to  realization  in  it. 
Thus  moral  necessity  has  now  reached  its  goal,  since  it  rules 
the  will ;  freedom,  too,  none  the  less,  has  reached  its  goal, 
since  it  has  obtained  possession  of  its  own  essential  nature, 
has  taken  up  into  itself  the  element  of  moral  necessity,  and  in 
imity  therewith  has  attained  realization.  United  to  the  good, 
man  is  now  united  to  God  and  also  to  himself,  to  his  own 
true  nature,  and  is  thus  in  a  state  of  harmony.  Hitherto 
man  was  in  a  state  of  dubiety,  fluctuating  in  his  choice,  at 
variance  with  himself  and  hence  unfree ;  but  now  he  is  in  his 
element,  and  experiences  for  the  first  time  the  true  energy 
and  enjoyment  of  life. 

The  transition  that  here  takes  place  must  not  be  made 
blindly ;  although  the  transition  to  Christian  faith  is  often 
demanded  as  an  act  of  blind  obedience.  It  must  take  place 
as  an  act  of  conscience,  demanded  morally,  an  act  of  moral 
insight  which  is  rendered  possible  by  the  perfect  self- 
revelation  of  divine  good  in  Christ.  As  regards  the  luill, 
moreover,  this  transition  must  not  be  effected  by  means  of 
purely  objective,  compulsory  forces.  For  in  that  case  the  will 
would  no  longer  be  true  to  its  own  nature,  but  would  be 
alienated  from  itself,  or  lose  itself  in  mere  passivity.  Just  as 
little,  of  course,  must  the  transition  occur  as  an  act  of  caprice, 
in  which  the  distinction  between  good  and  evil  is  regarded  as 
indifferent.  A  decision  arising  out  of  mere  caprice  would  not 
be  a  decision  in  the  right  sense  of  the  term.  On  the  con- 
trary, the  transition  must  be  effected  through  a  fundamental 
act  of  will  on  the  part  of  man,  in  which  he  decides  against 
evil  and  for  the  good  as  such,  for  the  good  as  the  truth  whose 
claims  alone  are  valid — an  act  in  which  he  resolves  to  shut 
himself  up  no  longer,  in  self-will  and  self-sufficient  folly, 
against  the  will  of  God,  nor  seek,  under  the  delusion  of 
imaginary  freedom,  to  be  a  self-centred  being.  He  must  con- 
sciously and  willingly  allow  himself  to  be  united  to  the  divine 
centre  of  e^cistence,  in  order  that  he  may  be  fdled  and  moved 
by  the  Spirit  of  God,  who  is  at  the  same  time  the  spirit  of  the 


282  §  30.    POSITIVE  DOCTEINE  OF  FKEEDOM. 

moral  order  of  the  world  as  a  M'hole.  Hence,  by  so  doing  he 
receives  his  proper  position  with  regard  to  the  world  and  to 
the  whole  moral  system  of  things. 

From  the  foregoing  discussion  it  will  now  be  evident  that 
the  doctrine,  "  man  can  indeed  produce  evil  of  himself,  but 
not  good,"  is  not  refuted  by  the  reply,  "  this  would  mean  that 
while  freedom  is  ascribed  to  man,  one  of  its  arms  is  cut  off, 
and  he  is  left  only  with  the  one  which  does  evil."  For 
although  man  cannot  be  said  to  produce  good  in  the  sense  in 
which  he  produces  evil,  since  God  is  the  positive  source  of  all 
good  (Jas.  i.  17,  18),  he  nevertheless  possesses  freedom  in 
the  sense  that  he  can  either  reject  the  good  which  is  ofiered 
him  or  allow  it  to  operate.  If  he  does  not  reject  it,  it  can  so 
attract  and  inspire  his  will  that  he  can  also  do  good  of  him- 
self. It  is  wrong  to  suppose  that  man  can  only  be  called 
free,  if  he  is  able  to  do  what  is  good  entirely  of  himself  and 
apart  from  God  altogether,  in  the  same  way  that  he  is 
certainly  able  to  do  what  is  evil  by  himself.  For  of  course  a 
human  will  is  all  that  is  required  for  the  performance  of  evil, 
in  which  man  retires  upon  himself  in  self-willed  isolation  from 
God  and  the  good ;  whereas  the  good  cannot  be  conceived  of 
as  existing  in  man  apart  from  a  conscious  or  unconscious 
communion  with  the  primal  source  of  good,  or  apart  from  a 
willingness  to  be  determined  by  its  objective  truth  and 
power. 

But  here  a  contradiction  seems  to  arise,  when  we  think 
of  the  completion  of  the  development  of  freedom.  If  the 
factors  we  have  described  really  belong  to  the  full  idea  of 
freedom,  then  these  must  be  preserved  in  the  perfect  form  of 
freedom.  This  causes  no  difficulty  so  far  as  essential  freedom 
is  concerned,  since  concrete  or  so-called  theological  freedom  is 
merely  the  realization  of  essential.  But  what  of  the  faculty 
of  choice  or  of  free  decision  ?  If  we  hold  that  the  faculty  of 
choice  still  continues  as  an  element  in  perfect  freedom,  then  it 
looks  as  if  we  must  say  that  even  the  perfect  man  is  always 
liable  to  fall.  Hence  it  seems  as  if  perfect  freedom  must 
exclude  freedom  of  choice.  On  the  other  hand,  if  we  suppose 
that  man  when  perfected  is  still  liable  to  change  and  exposed 
to  the  possibility  of  evil, — as  was  held,  e.g.,  by  Origen, — then 
the    good  has  not  yet  taken  secure  possession   of  him,  and 


§  31.    THE  MORAL  IDEAL.  283 

perfection  is  still  lacking.  Tlie  solution  of  the  problem  lies 
in  the  following  considerations.  The  faculty  of  choice  will 
indeed  continue,  but  it  will  no  longer  operate  in  an  arbitrary, 
isolated  fashion,  sundered  from  the  other  factors  in  freedom  ;  it 
will  no  longer  be  dissociated  from  moral  necessity,  from  the 
spirit  of  the  good.  It  will  continue  to  manifest  its  activity 
merely  in  discarding  every  false  possibility  and  in  choosing 
the  good.  When  once  man's  free  will  has  united  itself  with 
the  divine  will,  and  the  latter  has  wrought  in  him  delight  in 
the  good,  and  horror  and  detestation  of  evil,  then  his  will 
having  now  received  a  determinate  character,  has  lost  its 
liability  to  fall,  while  evil  has  lost  its  power  to  tempt  him. 
But  what  does  continue  is,  that  man  consciously  wills  the 
good  and  rejects  its  opposite ;  the  thought  of  evil,  as  the 
thought  of  what  must  be  repudiated,  serves  only  as  a  negative 
Ibil  to  man's  willinc;-  of  the  G;ood  as  such 


THIED   DIVISION. 

Cf.  §  9a. 

THE  ETHICAL  ORDER  OF  THE  WORLD,  AS  THE  PRACTICAL  GOAL 
OF  THE  MOVEMENT  OF  THE  MORAL  PROCESS,  OR  THE 
DOCTRINE  OF  THE  MORAL  IDEAL,  WHICH  IS  REALIZED  BY 
MEANS  OF  MORAL  ACTION. 

§  31. 

The  contents  of  the  Good, — which,  in  conformity  with  the 
purpose  of  creative  love,  have  to  come  to  realization 
through  the  co-operation  of  God  and  man, — or,  in  other 
words,  the  ethical  goal  of  the  world,  which  is  in  course 
of  attainment  in  spite  of  the  fact  of  sin,  is  the  actual 
existence  of  the  Kingdom  of  God  or  of  an  organized  life 
of  love  in  the  world,  in  which  nature  also  is  made  sub- 
servient to  moral  ends.  It  includes  chiefly — (1)  The 
realization  of  a  living  intercourse  between  God  and  man, 
in  which  man  enters  upon  a  filial  relationship  to  God, 


284  §  31.    THE  MORAL  IDEAL. 

and  his  religious  capacities  thereby  attain  to  full  reality 
in  holiness  and  blessedness.  (2)  The  right  regulation 
of  the  developed  energies  of  man,  so  that  they  become 
virtuous  energies.  (3)  The  moral  upbuilding  of  human 
life  in  moral  communities,  in  which  man's  subjective 
moral  capacities  come  forward  into  objective  existence, 
while  the  very  imperfect  communities  that  originate 
naturally  arrive  at  true  reality. 

1.  In  this  division  we  will  describe  the  end  or  result, 
which,  in  accordance  with  the  will  of  God,  is  ever  kept  in 
view  in  the  moral  process,  and  which  has  to  be  realized  by 
means  of  moral  action.  The  question  therefore  arises — What 
is  that  imperishable  product  which  is  to  be  the  outcome  of 
the  moral  process  ?  Thus  the  present  division  of  our  subject 
will  contain  the  doctrine  of  the  Chief  Good,  and  that  under 
the  point  of  view  of  Ethical  Eschatology.  Moreover,  the  goal 
of  this  process  is  not  only  an  object  for  idle  contemplation  ; 
it  is  also  a  task  assigned  to  man.  And  more  than  this,  since 
the  goal  which  is  to  be  attained  points  out  the  road  which 
leads  to  it,  it  at  the  same  time  lays  down  the  particular  task 
which  belongs  to  each  stage  of  approximation.  For  in  this 
process,  that  stage  must  first  be  reached  which  is  the  condition 
or  presupposition  of  what  follows.  Accordingly,  in  describing 
the  world-goal  considered  as  a  task  in  which  each  one  has 
his  part  to  play,  the  contents  of  the  moral  law  will  also  be 
unfolded.  In  our  doctrine  of  the  law  and  of  conscience,  it 
was  the  formal  side  of  the  law  which  we  had  to  consider. 
For  there  we  M'ere  concerned  with  a  description  of  the  factors, 
by  means  of  which  in  general  a  moral  process  can  take  place. 
But  at  present  the  contents  of  the  law  must  be  definitely 
dealt  with,  and  that  under  the  aspect  of  the  moral  ideal  of 
the  world — an  ideal  which,  as  has  been  shown,  is  the  world's 
task,  necessary,  unconditioned  and  universal,  but  which  also 
takes  organic  shape,  that  is,  resolves  itself  into  every  variety 
of  individual  form. 

2.  Now  with  regard  to  the  goal  which  has  to  be  attained  by 
means  of  the  moral  process,  very  different  vieivs  have  prevailed 
both  within  and  without  the  Church. 


ROMAN  CATHOLIC  DOCTRINE.  285 

(a)  The  old  classical  world  knows  of  nothing  higher  than 
the  State.  Here  all  moral  culture  and  moral  action  are  made 
to  conform  to  the  idea  of  the  State  and  its  interests.  In 
jDarticular,  since  the  State  accomplishes  the  subjugation  of 
nature  to  the  largest  extent,  the  goal  of  humanity  is  con- 
ceived of  as  consisting  in  this,  that  mankind  should,  as  a 
State,  acquire  full  dominion  over  nature.* 

(Jj)  In  the  Christian  era,  the  Church  in  its  Eoman  Catholic 
form  now  comes  forward  in  opposition  to  the  State,  claiming 
that  she  is  the  chief  good,  and  that  everything  outside  her 
pale  is  worthless,  or  else  intended  wholly  and  simply  for  her 
service.  She  takes  up,  as  a  spiritual  institution,  the  rolo 
which  the  State  played  in  the  old  world.  The  very  pre- 
dicates of  unity,  universality,  necessity,  and  unconditionally 
binding  power,  wliich  belong  to  the  moral  law,  she  applies  to 
herself  as  being  herself  the  contents  of  the  true  law  of  the 
world.  What  is  not  connected  with  the  Church  is  unspiritual, 
and  is  treated  fundamentally  as  worldly,  profane.  Thus, 
between  the  pre-Christian  ethics  of  the  classical  age  and  the 
ethics  of  Eoman  Catholicism  there  is  a  fundamental  opposi- 
tion, as  regards  their  estimation  of  the  natural  in  its  relation 
to  the  human  spirit.  Both,  however,  are  at  one  in  this — that 
in  their  ethical  representation  of  the  world  the  individual 
personality  is  everywhere  thrust  into  the  background,  behind 
the  universal.  Individual  rights  are  absorbed  in  the  whole, 
which  in  the  one  case  is  the  State,  in  the  other  the  Church. 
The  consequence  is  that  the  Eoman  Catholic  Church  unites 
a  false  this-ivorld  viciu  of  the  chief  good,  that  is,  of  the  Church, 
with  a  false  other-world  vieiu  of  it  as  regards  the  individual  'per- 
sonality.  On  the  one  hand,  the  Church  in  its  official  capacity 
adapts  itself  even  to  worldly  forms,  and  seeks  to  be  the 
supreme  power  on  earth,  over  against  the  individual  as  well 
as  the  State ;  while,  on  the  other  hand,  he  who  is  concerned 
about  the  assurance  of  salvation,  which  is  the  highest  personal 
good,  is  pointed   away  to  another  world,  where  salvation   is 

^  In  Christendom,  Theodore  of  Mopsuestia  was  the  first  to  adopt  this  point 
of  view  ;  after  him  the  Socinians.  According  to  Theodore,  man's  similitude  to 
God  consists  in  his  having  dominion  over  nature  ;  as  God  is  the  ruler  of  the 
Avorld,  so  man  is  destined,  as  a  subordinate  deity  as  it  were,  to  become  lord  of 
the  earth. 


286       §  31.    THE  MOPiAL  IDEAL.       REFOKMATION  DOCTRINE. 

held  otit  in  prospect  and  has  to  be  won  by  meritorious  works, 
chiefly  of  the  nature  of  self-abnegation  and  renunciation  of 
the  world. 

(c)  With  the  Information  a  new  antithesis  appears.  Per- 
sonality assumes  its  rights  over  against  the  universal  in  both 
its  forms ;  at  first  as  against  the  Church,  afterwards  as  against 
the  State  as  well.  In  agreement  with  the  gospel,  the  Eefor- 
mation  transfers  the  assurance  of  salvation,  and  therewith  the 
supreme  personal  good,  the  ^ayt]  aloovio^i,  back  to  the  present 
world ;  but  it  must  be  admitted  tliat  it  does  so  in  such  a 
way  as  to  attach  leading  importance  to  individual  ethics. 
Through  the  assurance  of  salvation  the  individual  receives  a 
position  of  independence  over  against  the  Church.  The 
moral  spheres  of  life  are  released  from  the  guardianship  of 
the  Church,  but  the  Christian  principle,  which  has  again 
been  brought  forward  and  made  the  principle  of  Protes- 
tantism, is  not  forthwith  turned  to  account  in  these  spheres, 
nor  made  to  find  its  development  in  them.  In  the  Lutheran 
Church  especially,  the  self-sufilicingness  of  faith  betrays  for  a 
long  time  a  certain  indifference  towards  the  ethical  construc- 
tion of  the  different  departments  of  human  life.  Attention 
is  paid  to  these  only  as  means  for  the  cultivation  of  faith,  as 
affording  a  field  for  its  exercise.  In  faith  man  is  already  in 
possession  of  the  chief  good  ;  and  so  his  endeavour  is  rather 
to  preserve  it  in  spite  of  the  activities  of  social  life  than  to 
make  the  divine  substance  of  faith  become  of  any  real  service 
to  them.  The  proper  work  of  life  is  as  good  as  ended  when 
justifying  faith  has  been  won,  so  that  afterwards  there  can 
really  be  nothing  better  for  the  individual  believer  than 
death.  It  is  only  in  the  Reformed  Church  that  faith  operates 
as  a  regenerating  principle  for  the  spheres  of  public  life  ;  in 
the  Lutheran  its  efficiency  is  almost  entirely  confined  to  the 
religious  life  of  the  individual,  and  to  the  two  moral  com- 
munities, Marriage  and  the  Family.  Nay,  in  the  Lutheran 
Church  of  the  iVtli  and  18th  centuries,  the  full  assurance  of 
individual  faith  itself  declined,  and  although  the  tendency 
which  began  with  Spener  renewed  it  and  laid  stress  upon 
sanctification,  still  little  advance  was  made  beyond  the  sancti- 
fication  of  the  individual.  In  an  ethical  upbuilding  of  the 
world  in  a  Christian  sense  only  a  partial  interest  was  taken 


LATER  THEORIES,       SCHLEIEEMACHEK.  287 

— viz.  only  so  far  as  the  organization  of  the  Church  was 
concerned  ;  for  which  purpose  the  Church  carried  into  effect 
the  evangelical  doctrine  of  the  universl  priesthood  of  believers, 
and  called  in  the  laity  to  her  aid. 

Thus  in  the  older  form  of  Protestantism,  the  joy  that  is 
found  in  the  experience  of  salvation  was  not  sufficiently 
allowed  to  expand  into  the  impulse  and  desire  to  conquer 
the  regions  of  outward  life.  The  natural  consequence  was, 
that  what  remained  unsubdued,  viz.  the  worldly  principle, 
which  was  no  longer  held  in  restraint  by  the  Church  but  was 
left  entirely  to  itself,  now  completed  its  emancipation  and  took 
possession  of  the  unoccupied  ground,  in  the  two  forms  of 
worldly  Objectivism  and  Subjectivism.  The  first  of  these 
appeared  in  the  absolutism  which,  beginning  with  Louis 
XIV.,  penetrated  into  Germany  and  England ;  and  in 
absolutist  theories  of  the  State,  which  made  not  only  in- 
dividuals but  also  religion  and  the  Church  unconditionally 
subject  to  the  State.  These  reached  their  harshest  shape 
in  the  theory  of  Hobbes,  who,  in  opposition  to  the  extrava- 
gances of  the  English  Eevolution  period,  set  up  the  State  as 
a  God  upon  earth,  ruling  with  absolute  authority  all  the 
outward  actions  of  man.  The  second  form  appeared  in  the 
18th  century,  when  Eousseau  in  his  Contrat  social  made 
Marriage,  State,  and  Church  all  alike  rest  upon  a  mere  sub- 
jective agreement  between  individuals,  and  thus  abandoned 
their  objective  validity  to  caprice  and  selfishness.  A  reac- 
tion against  this  subjectivism  took  its  rise  with  Hegel  and 
Schelling.  They,  however,  again  made  the  State  the  universal 
of  the  moral  world,  although  they  did  so  in  a  more  worthy 
form,  and  assigned  to  the  State  especially  higher  functions 
than  had  previously  been  given  it.  But  the  exercise  of 
absolute  power  by  the  State  is  destructive  of  the  rights  of 
religion,  of  the  Church,  and  of  the  individual  as  well  ;  the 
necessary  result  of  such  a  theory  is  the  introduction — though 
in  a  nobler  form — of  pre-Christian  forms  of  error,  and  the 
apotheosis  of  the  State. 

Here,  too,  it  is  Schleiermacher  who  marks  a  decisive 
turning-point  in  thought.  On  the  one  hand,  he  goes  back  to 
the  Eeformation  principle  of  the  importance  of  the  individual, 
who,  even  now   in   this   present   world,  becomes  by  faith  a 


288  §  31.    THE  MORAL  IDEAL. 

partaker  of  the  Holy  Spirit  and  of  eternal  life ;  while,  on  the 
other  hand,  he  holds  that  the  new  life  of  the  believer  must  he 
applied  like  leaven  to  effect  the  moral  transformation  of  the 
world.  Thus,  starting  from  Individual  Ethics,  which  must 
certainly  be  taken  as  a  foundation,  he  advances  to  so-called 
Social  Ethics.  He  brings  Christian  faith  into  intimate  con- 
nection with  the  objective  moral  world,  and  also  with  nature, 
and  regards  moral  communities  not  merely  as  means  for  the 
subjects  who  compose  them,  but  also  as  ends  which  have  a 
moral  worth  of  their  own.  Nor  does  he  thereby  deprive 
individuals  of  all  reference  to  self ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  just 
according  to  the  measure  of  their  moral  individuality  as 
believers  that  they  react  upon  the  communities  of  which  they 
are  members.  Thus  there  is  opened  up  for  the  principle  of 
faith  a  career  of  fruitful  activity  in  the  objective  world ;  the 
opposition  between  the  Universal  or  Identical,  and  the 
Personal  or  even  the  Individual,  is  in  principle  reconciled. 
It  belongs  to  the  truth  of  each  single  personality  that  the 
spirit  of  the  community  should  rule  within  it ;  it  belongs  to 
the  truth  of  each  community  that  its  work  should  be  carried 
on  by  free  personalities.  He  likewise  guards  the  independence 
of  separate  communities  as  against  each  otlier.  The  life  here 
is  to  become  the  representation  of  the  ^o)7j  aloovto'i,  which  is 
already  in  existence  in  the  Church. 

But  Schleiermacher,  it  must  be  admitted,  has  carried  out 
this  thought  at  the  expense  of  what  is  reserved  for  the 
world  to  come.  This  is  seen  in  the  way  in  which  he,  and 
after  him  Rothe,  attempt  to  overcome  the  opposition  between 
the  world  of  nature  and  the  vvorld  of  mind.  According 
to  Schleiermacher,  the  moral  task  assigned  to  humanity 
consists  in  this — that  mind  shall  take  possession  of  nature 
and  make  of  it  a  body,  as  it  were,  for  humanity,  shall  animate 
it  by  means  of  a  process  of  moral  assimilation,  and  thus  trans- 
figure it  by  its  representing  and  organizing  activity.-^  Mind 
is  in  this  way  to  attain  to  organized  and  completely  developed 
objective  existence,  to  its  identification,  as  it  were,  with 
nature,  to  the  end  that  ethics  and  physics  may  be  reduced  to 
unity.  But  now,  inasmuch  as,  according  to  Schleiermacher's 
Christian  ethics,  it  is  the  State  to  which  the  moral  task 
1  [See  p.  99,  footnote.— Te.] 


eothe's  conceptiox  of  the  ethical  ideal.  289 

belongs  of  accomplishing  the  subjugation  of  nature,  this  has  a 
dangerous  sound  for  the  Church,  since  to  the  latter  also 
nature  is  necessary  in  order  to  afford  it  a  form  of  manifesta- 
tion. With  Schleiermacher  himself  this  danger  is  lessened 
by  the  independence  which  he  reserves  for  the  Church. 
Eothe,  on  the  contrary,  starting  from  similar  ideas  as  to  the 
moral  task  which  mankind  has  to  fulfil  with  regard  to  nature, 
makes  the  Church  disappear  in  the  Christian  State.-^ 

Eothe  carries  out  with  even  greater  rigour  this  idea  of  the 
spiritualization  of  nature  as  the  moral  work  which  man  has 
to  do.  He  regards  it  as  the  goal  of  the  world.  To  him  spirit 
does  not  exist  until  there  has  been  this  union  and  inter- 
penetration  of  the  ideal  and  the  real.  This  takes  place  by 
means  of  the  moral  process.  That  process  originates  spirit 
out  of  matter.  In  fact,  matter  is  so  constituted  that  those 
elements  in  it  which  are  capable  of  assimilation  are  destined 
to  become  spirit,  while  the  human  personality  is  destined  to 
become  spirit  through  its  appropriation  of  matter.  By  means 
of  the  moral  process  a  spiritual  body  is  formed,  and  its  forma- 
tion is,  for  Eothe,  the  task  to  be  accomplished,  or  the  result 
of  the  moral  process.  But  since  the  formation  of  this  body 
goes  on  without  our  knowledge,  it  might  be  a  result  that 
arises  of  itself  from  the  moral  process,  and  in  that  case  it 
ought  not  to  be  advanced  as  the  proper  ethical  task  of  man, 
but  only  as  something  ordained  and  brought  to  pass  by  God. 
There  is  no  doubt  that  the  moral  work  which  man  has  to 
perform  includes  nature  in  its  scope  ;  further,  in  consequence 
of  actions  passing  over  into  habits,  there  ensues,  as  has 
already  been  shown,  an  incorporation  of  spirit  with  nature, — 
a  result  which  is  produced  unconsciously.  But  the  contents 
of  the  ethical  goal  of  the  world  or  of  the  JMoral  Ideal  embrace 
not  merely  man's  relations  to  nature,  but  also  and  principally 
his  relations  to  God  and  to  the  human  race ;  and  it  is  by 
means  of  these  latter  relations  that  nature  can  everywhere  be 
made  subservient  to  moral  ends.  The  complete  spiritualiza- 
tion of  nature,  moreover,  is  something  which  we  must  not 
expect  as  the  direct  outcome  of  a  moral  process,  but  as  the 
result  of  an  act  of  God  which  will  usher  in  a  new  era  of  the 
world. 
'  Cf.  Ethik,  2nd  ed.  §  299  f.     [Theologische  Encydopadie,  pp.  83-94.— Ed.] 

T 


290  §  31,    THE  MORAL  IDEAL. 

Note. — When  we  survey  all  these  different  conceptions  of  the 
goal  of  the  world  or  highest  good,  we  have  the  following 
results : — (1)  That  conception  of  it  is  defective  which,  at  the 
expense  of  the  individual  personality,  defines  the  chief  good  in 
a  one-sided  objective  manner, — whether  this  objective  good  be 
the  State  or  the  Church, — or  relegates  it,  so  far  as  the  individual 
is  concerned,  to  the  future  world.  (2)  A  one-sided  subjective 
conception  of  the  ethical  ideal  is  also  unsatisfactory  ;  most 
strikingly  so  when  it  appears  in  the  form  of  mere  eudsemonism 
or  worldliness  ;  but  also  when  it  takes  the  form  of  maintaining 
that  the  mere  subjective,  free  personality  is  the  chief  good,  and 
that  all  objective  communities  arise  out  of  individual  caprice  or 
contract.  (3)  The  basis  for  the  true  definition  of  the  chief  good 
was  laid  down  at  the  Eeformation,  and  consists  in  justifying 
faith,  the  blessing  of  reconciliation,  of  which  faith  is  already  a 
partaker  in  the  present  world.  This  blessing  is  not  of  a  merely 
subjective  kind,  either  in  the  sense  of  being  self-produced  or  of 
being  something  that  renders  the  believer  self-sufficient,  but  is 
union  with  God  and  the  possession  of  eternal  life  through  Him. 
But  this  divine  life  must  also  unfold  itself ;  it  must  not  shut 
itself  up  in  self-contained  isolation  ;  but  nnist  rather  seek  and 
find  its  true  relation  to  nature  and  to  objective  moral  com- 
munities. 

3.  From  this  historical  survey  we  now  proceed  to  the 
correct  definition  of  the  goal  of  the  world,  and  in  doing  so  we 
will  first  of  all  consider  the  Biblical  Doctrine  on  the  subject. 
The  all-comprehensive  expression  for  the  ethical  goal  of  the 
world,  which  must  be  included  in  the  divine  decree,  is  the 
6e\7)fjLa  Oeou}  This  O'ekrj^a  takes  two  forms ;  on  the  one 
hand,  it  is  a  will  that  makes  requirements,  issues  commands ; 
on  the  other,  it  is  a  will  that  gives  promises.  In  its  first 
form  it  aims  at  producing  moral  activity  on  the  part  of  man, 
whetlier  of  a  negative  or  positive  kind ;  in  its  second  form  it 
points  to  an  act  on  the  part  of  God  towards  which  man  must 
take  up  a  receptive  attitude.  But  both  of  these  are  joined  in 
the  very  closest  way.  In  the  Old  Testament,  under  the  law, 
the  Eequirement  predominates;  although  at  the  same  time 
tlie  Promise  is  not  wanting,  but  both  precedes  and  follows  the 
law.  In  the  New  Testament  it  is  the  divine  act,  the  fulfil- 
ment of  the  promise,  that  comes  first  and  lays  the  foundation 
for  everything  else.  But  here,  too,  the  act  of  God  and  the 
act  of  man  are  most  intimately  joined.  In  the  first  place, 
1  Cf.  Schraid,  De  notione  legis. 


BIBLICAL  DOCTRINE.  291 

that  which  is  simply  and  solely  God's  promise  and  act  becomes 
nevertheless  a  demand  made  upon  man,  that  is,  upon  his 
living  receptivity.  He  must,  before  everything  else,  accept 
the  fundamental  gift  of  reconciliation  in  vTraKorj  iriaTeaxi — 
there  is  a  v6iio<i  •KLarew'i  (Eom.  i.  5,  xvi.  26;  1  Pet.  i.  22). 
Faith  is  also  a  work,  even  the  basis  of  all  other  work  (John 
vi.  27-29);  a  work  of  God  in  which  man  also  has  something 
to  do.  But,  in  the  second  place,  the  conclusion  of  the  whole 
matter  has  not  been  reached  when  the  gift  of  God  has  been 
received.  That  work  which  God  purposes  to  accomplish  in 
humanity,  the  work  of  forming  a  new  moral  world,  a  second 
creation, — this  must  be  taken  up  by  believers,  and  made  their 
task,  their  work ;  they  must  not  idly  rest  in  the  blessedness 
of  faith.  On  the  first  point  see,  e.g.,  Matt,  xviii.  14;  John 
vi.  39;  Eph.  i.  5,  9,  11  ;  Col.  i.  9;  Heb.  x.  10.  On  the 
second.  Matt.  vi.  10,  vii.  21,  xii.  50;  John  iv.  34,  v.  30, 
vi.  38,  vii.  17,  ix.  31.  This,  therefore,  is  the  relation  between 
the  divine  and  the  human  dekrifia  and  work  ;  receiving  the 
gift  of  God  to  begin  with,  man  must  now  proceed  to  make 
the  divine  OiXTj/na  his  own,  in  its  full  extent,  and  herewith 
the  chief  good  begins  to  be  realized  in  this  present  world. 

We  now  proceed  to  consider  the  contents  of  the  divine 
6ek7]fjba  in  general.  These  receive  all-comprehensive  expres- 
sion in  the  biblical  phrase  ^aaiKela  deov  or  ovpavwv.  The 
final  perfection  of  this  kingdom  belongs  to  the  future,  and 
even  to  the  world  to  come  (Matt.  vii.  21,  viii.  11,  xxv.  34). 
Its  commencement,  however,  takes  place,  according  to  the 
New  Testament,  in  the  present  world,  and,  since  the  time  of 
Christ,  has  begun  to  have  a  real  existence  among  men  (Matt. 
iv.  17,  V.  3  (icTTLv),  xi.  11  f.,  xvi.  19,  xviii.  3).  It  is  destined 
to  spread  unceasingly  (Mark  iv.  26  ;  Luke  xvii.  21  ;  Matt, 
xiii.  31-33);  among  all  nations  (Matt.  xiii.  33),  as  well  as 
over  all  the  spheres  of  human  life  (Matt,  xiii,  23),  and  also 
of  external  nature.  Of  this  jSacrtXeia,  whidi  is  a  vigorous 
organism,  the  main  divisions  are  as  follows. 

(«)  First  of  all,  communion  with  God,  in  which  man 
becomes  the  possessor  of  salvation.  Here  it  is  willingness  to 
receive  that  is  of  highest  importance.  God,  on  His  side,  lays 
the  foundation  for  this  communion  by  His  prevenient  love 
(John  iii.    16;  1   John  iv.    10);  by  the    atonement,   which 


292  §  31.    THE  MOEAL  IDEAL.       BIBLICAL  COCTRINE. 

overcomes  the  obstacles  of  sin  and  guilt  (2  Cor.  v.  16-21). 
In  the  alfia  Xpiarov  (Rom.  iii.  25)  He  seeks  to  be  our  Father, 
and  intends  us  to  be  His  children,  and  to  desire  so  to  be 
(Rom.  vi.  1-6  ;  2  Cor.  v.  19  f.).  Nay,  He  will  take  up  His 
abode  within  us,  as  His  living  temples  (John  xiv.  23,  xvii. 
2 If.;   1  Cor.  iii.  16,  vi.  19). 

Q))  Along  with  this,  in  the  absolute  sphere  man  is  restored 
to  his  true  immediate  relation  to  God;  the  normal  and  funda- 
mental moral  relation  in  which  he  stands  to  God  is  that  of  a 
son.  Moreover,  when  man  is  thus  reconciled,  and  has  become 
a  child  of  God,  the  new  man  begins  to  live  within  him 
(Col.  iii.  9  f.), — the  true,  immortal  personality,  which  now 
lives  and  grows,  purifying  man's  energies,  and  harmoniously 
developing  them  into  pure  and  perfect  efficiency  (1  Cor.  iii. 
IC;  Eph.  ii.  10,  iv.  21  f.). 

(c)  Lastly,  in  all  the  moral  relations  which  the  believer 
holds,  whether  to  other  men  or  to  communities,  he  is  enabled, 
by  the  indwelling  of  the  Holy  Spirit,  to  bring  forth  tlie  fruits 
of  the  Spirit  (Eph.  v.  9).  In  these  relations  he  does  not 
merely  assert  himself  as  an  individual,  but  also  devotes  him- 
self to  the  duties  they  impose,  in  a  spirit  of  self-sacrificing 
love,  arising  out  of  love  to  God.  The  social  impulse  of  the 
Christian,  or  Christian  love,  finds  its  first  sphere  of  exercise 
in  the  community  formed  for  the  purpose  of  rendering  praise 
and  thanksgiving  to  God  for  the  gift  of  salvation,  that  is  to 
say,  in  the  cultivation  of  Christian  brotherhood  in  the  Church. 
This  is  a  new,  independent  institution,  belonging  to  the  higher 
stage.  For  he  who  has  come  to  know  God  as  his  Father 
and  himself  as  God's  child,  loves,  by  virtue  of  the  higher 
spiritual  nature  which  is  in  him,  every  one  who  like  himself 
has  been  begotten  of  God  (1  John  v.  1).  Further,  the  gospel 
sanctions  and  confirms  all  the  natural  relations  and  arrange- 
ments of  life,  as  well  as  the  various  circumstances  and 
vocations  which  God  has  assigned  to  different  individuals. 
Thus,  with  regard  to  civil  authority  (Matt.  xxii.  2 1 ;  Rom. 
xiii.  1  f.) ;  the  relations  of  husband  and  wife,  of  parents  and 
children  (1  Tim.  iv.  3:  dcpecSla  aooixaro^,  Col.  ii.  23);  the 
relation  of  servants  and  masters  (Philem.).  On  the  other  hand, 
a  nciv  luay  of  looking  at  everything  is  introduced.  Everything 
is  regarded  under  the  aspect  of  v:ovship  (Rom.  xii.  1  f.) ;  the 


CONTENTS  OF  THE  MORAL  IDEAL.  293 

moral  upbuilding  of  the  whole  person,  whether  in  the  way  of 
enjoyment,  of  rest,  or  of  activity  (1  Tim.  iv.  3) ;  and  in  like 
manner,  whatever  is  done  for  the  common  welfare.  The  same 
thing  is  expressed  when  it  is  said  that  everything  is  to  be 
done  in  the  name  of  Jesus  (Col.  iii.  17).  To  the  idea  of 
the  kingdom  of  God  as  an  all-embracing,  objective  end,  there 
corresponds  on  the  subjective  side  the  idea  of  an  all-embracing 
worship,  in  which  man's  whole  heart  and  mind  is  engaged, 
and  which  enters  even  into  the  duties  of  his  vocation  and  his 
moral  enjoyments.  Nature,  too,  is  included  in  this  ^acriXeia, 
regarded  in  its  consummation,  for  then  she  will  be  released 
from  her  present  transitoriness  (Rom.  viii.  18  f.;  Eev.  xxi.  1  ; 
2  Pet.  iii.  13  ;  Isa.  Ixv.  17,  Ixvi.  22). 

4.  After  this  biblical  statement,  a  few  words  will  suffice 
for  the  tlietic  [positive]  2^'^^(^sentation  of  our  subject,  especially 
as  in  what  follows  we  shall  have  to  treat  it  concretely  and  in 
detail.  The  world's  ideal,  or  the  kingdom  of  God,  is  con- 
tained in  the  purpose  which  God  had  in  creating  the  world. 
Now,  since  it  was  from  love  that  God  willed  the  creation  of 
the  world,  He  could  not  have  meant  it  to  be  merely  an  object 
for  His  love,  and  nothing  more.  He  must  have  created  it  to 
give  as  well  as  to  receive  love,  in  order  that  it — and  indeed 
every  single  personality  in  it — might  become  both  an  ultimate 
end,  because  an  end  for  love,  and  also  a  mirror,  or,  as  it  were, 
the  continuation  of  His  love.  Hence  it  follows  that  not  only 
can  dominion  over  nature  not  be  the  ethical  ideal,  and 
eudffimonism  still  less  so,  but  also  that  neither  the  State 
by  itself  nor  any  one  of  the  moral  spheres  can  constitute  it. 
Even  the  Church  must  not  claim  to  be  called  the  sole  moral 
product.  Everything  will  alike  belong  to  the  kingdom  of  God 
which  can  be  a  form  of  the  life  of  love.  It  follows,  too,  that 
no  community  must  make  the  individual  a  mere  instrument 
for  its  own  ends ;  and  conversely,  that  the  individual  must 
not  regard  the  community  as  only  a  means  to  be  used  for  his 
own  advantage.  This  is  guarded  against  by  the  spirit  of  holy 
love  (Justice  being  an  element  in  this  love),  which  restores  in 
the  individual  the  image  of  God,  and  thus  makes  him  an 
ultimate  end.  The  community  likewise  participates  in  this 
spirit  of  love,  and  so  becomes  an  ultimate  end  also. 

Moral    personality    is    certainly  the    basis    for    all    moral 


294  §  31.    THE  MOEAL  IDEAL. 

production.  It  is  only  in  persons  that  love  can  dwell ;  the 
new  personality  is  therefore  the  first  prerequisite  for  the 
realization  of  the  kingdom  of  God,  and  is  in  fact  the  begin- 
ning of  its  actual  existence.  It  is  the  good  tree  (Matt.  vii. 
16  f.),  its  cultivation  is  therefore  the  first  work  of  all.  Hence 
the  word  of  Christ  addresses  itself  in  the  first  place  to  individuals, 
to  establish  love  in  their  hearts  through  repentance  and  faith ; 
it  does  not  fonnd  institutions  to  tegin  ivith.  But  as  soon  as 
the  new,  loving  personality  has  come  into  being,  it  will  now 
— inasmuch  as  it  has  its  source  in  and  is  a  copy  of  the 
perfections  of  God — become  inspired  with  wisdom,  and  forth- 
with prove  itself  to  be  a  principle  that  is  able  to  bring  the 
life  of  the  individual,  the  life  of  communities,  and  man's 
relations  to  nature,  into  harmonious  moral  order. 

The  love  of  the  new  personality  turns  first  of  all,  in  devo- 
tion and  thanksgiving,  to  God  the  Creator  as  its  Father,  and 
seeks  to  do  His  6e\v/Jt-a,  as  He  has  revealed  it  in  the  word 
and  example  of  the  Son.  Thus  the  fundamental  moral  activity 
of  the  Christian  is  a  religious  one,  consisting  in  love  to  God 
(1  John  iv.  10).  But  this  love  to  God  now  leads  him  to 
conform  his  will,  with  regard  both  to  himself  and  to  all 
external  things,  to  the  mind  and  will  of  the  all-wise  and 
all-loving  God,  and  to  His  OeXrjfia  as  already  revealed  in  the 
creation  and  constitution  of  the  world,  and  more  fully  in  the 
conscience  and  history  of  man.  True  love  to  God  there- 
fore includes  true  love  to  oneself  and  one's  neighbour  (Matt. 
x*ii.  37f. ;  1  John  v.  1),  and  thus  it  gives  the  individual 
and  communities  their  due  position  of  co-ordination.  One  and 
the  same  spirit  of  love  binds  together  the  numerous  energies 
of  the  individual  in  harmonious  unity,  and  employs  all  the 
manifold  varieties  of  individual  character  in  the  service  of 
that  organized  life  of  love,  that  ethical  cosmos  or  Jcingdom,  in 
which  all  human  capacities  reach  their  full  natural  activity, 
and  which  also  has  everything  prepared  for  it  which  is 
necessary  to  its  growth.  The  world  cannat  fail  to  reach  its 
goal ;  the  infinite  creative  power  and  wisdom  of  God,  as  well 
as  the  ranks  of  the  eeons,  are  enlisted  in  its  service.  And  so 
one  day  God  will  see  reflected  from  His  world,  in  the  mani- 
fold diversity  of  its  organized  life,  an  image  of  His  own 
perfections — created  indeed,  but  still  pure  and  majestic ;  and 


PERMANENCE  OF  EARTHLY  PRODUCTIONS.        295 

humanity,  together  with  the  higher  world  of  spirits,  will  form 
the  perfected  city  of  God,  in  which  nothing  will  be  lost  that 
was  ever  won  by  moral  effort  upon  earth. 

5.  But  now,  when  we  turn  our  attention  to  the  transitori- 
ness  and  death  which  are  in  the  world,  the  question  arises — 
How  can  we  ascribe  an  inward  moral,  and  therefoi-e  eternal 
worth  to  earthly  products,  relations,  and  societies  in  themselves, 
seeing  that  they  are  conditioned  by  nature,  which  is  fleeting, 
and  by  matter  ?  It  is  true  that  persons  alone  of  all  earthly 
e;dstences  have  immortality,  and  even  they  only  or  prin- 
cipally so  far  as  the  mind  is  concerned.  Nevertheless  we 
must  limit  the  assertion  of  the  perishable  value  of  all  earthly 
works,  relations,  and  societies,  unless  we  are  willing  to  rob 
them  of  that  which  is,  as  it  were,  tlie  very  pith  of  their  life, 
and  to  reduce  them  to  mere  husks,  empty  instruments  that 
are  in  themselves  worthless  and  indifferent.  Each  single 
external  work  as  such  does  indeed  pass  away  sooner  or  later 
in  the  course  of  history  ;  but  in  anotlier  respect  it  is  imperish- 
able. Every  work  which  is  the  expression  of  mind — whether 
in  art  or  science,  in  the  State,  the  family,  or  the  Churcli — is, 
by  the  act  which  throws  it  into  objective  shape,  set  free  from 
that  which  is  personal,  the  subjectivity  of  its  author.  Through 
this  release  it  attains  that  form  in  which  it  becomes  an  object 
of  x^erception,  and  so  an  operative  factor  in  history,  a  leaven 
or  seed  deposited  in  the  minds  of  men.  When  it  has  reached 
this  stage,  in  which  it  is  set  loose  from  the  person  of  its 
author, — nay,  even  from  the  individual,  external  form  in 
which  the  work  appeared,  and  which,  it  may  be,  quickly 
passes  away, — it  now  proceeds  to  act  independently  like  a 
kindling  spark  ;  it  becomes  incorporated  as  an  element  with 
the  further  progress  of  mankind,  and  helps  to  determine  their 
succeeding  productions,  so  that  these  can  only  be  understood 
when  its  influence  is  taken  into  account.  Thus  the  later  and 
the  earlier  generations  of  men  are  linked  together  as  partners 
in  one  great  moral  work;  in  the  coursii  of  which,  indeed,  not 
only  individual  persons  but  also  their  works — as  single, 
isolated  productions — vanish  from  the  scene  ;  but  in  which, 
nevertheless,  they  possess  a  certain  immortality  as  operative 
elements  in  the  moral  progress  of  mankind.  Thus  nothing 
great   that   has   once   happened   is    ever  lost    to   humanity ; 


296         §  31.    THE  MOEAL  IDEAL.       EARTHLY  PRODUCTIONS 

humanity  takes  it  up  into  her  life,  either  unconsciously  or  in 
conscious  remembrance,  and  there  it  continues  to  work  unseen. 

Matter^  and  nature  also  render  essential  service  in  this 
process,  since  it  is  only  through  them  that  what  is  inward 
and  subjective  can  be  made  objective  in  fruitful  productions, 
whether  as  regards  the  family,  the  State,  art,  science,  or  the 
Church.  It  is  true,  no  doubt,  that  the  objective  form  thus 
obtained  is  no  more  than  an  intermediate  element  in  the 
process,  and  is  therefore  transitory, — as  indeed  the  work  itself 
only  expresses  a  single  mood  or  side  of  the  man  who  produced 
it,  and  is  never  his  whole  personality  made  objective.  But  as 
soon  as  what  is  subjective  has  been  made  objective,  and  has 
thus  been  taken  up  into  the  nature  of  things,  then  mutable 
though  nature  be,  it  still  holds  it  fast  for  a  length  of  time 
sufficient  to  allow  it  to  be  clearly  perceived,  and  to  be  carried 
into  the  minds  of  other  men.  By  this  means  a  lasting 
influence  is  secured  for  human  productions. 

Moreover,  with  regard  also  to  individuals  themselves,  who 
are  the  authors  of  moral  productions,  the  words  must  hold 
true,  "  their  works  follow  them "  (Eev.  xiv.  1 3).  These 
endure  even  beyond  death  in  the  personalities  whose  works 
they  are.  They  are  the  spiritual  profit  which  these  personalities 
have  made ;  they  give  them  a  moral  character,  and  thus  form 
their  stock  of  spiritual  capital  (§  11,  7)  and  render  possible 
still  greater  moral  productions  to  come.  "  Thou  hast  been 
faithful  over  a  few  things ;  I  will  make  thee  ruler  over  many 
things"  (Matt.  xxv.  21).  Here,  too,  matter  and  nature^ 
prove  to  be  essential  conditions  of  acquiring  such  moral  gains. 
For  thought  and  will  do  not  attain  full  strength  and  clearness 
until  they  reach  complete  objectivity  in  the  world  of  sense. 
The  perishable  nature  of  such  objectivity  makes  no  difference 
to  this  truth.  On  the  contrary,  the  very  transitoriness  of  its 
forms,  its  plasticity,  assists  us  in  learning  to  treat  it  as  that 
which  it  is  intended  to  be — a  means  and  not  an  end. 

The  same  thing  holds  good  also  of  all  moral  communities. 
Their  present  earthly  form,  in  which  they  are  involved  with 
nature  and  matter,  is  a  preparation  for  their  final  perfection  in 
the  kingdom  of  God.  Moral  employment  in  connection  with 
them  is  thus  of  eternal  moral  value  ;  and  that  not  simply  in 

1  Cf.  §  9.  2.  *  Cf.  §  9.  2. 


IN  THE  FINAL  CONSUMMATION.  297 

the  formal  sense  that  they  afford  the  individual  a  means  of 
exercising  his  virtue,  but  also  with  reference  to  the  actual 
work  achieved.  For  in  these  communities  the  Christian  sees 
even  now  the  actual  beginnings,  the  typical  lealization  of  the 
heavenly  kingdom  of  God,  and  it  is  this  which  he  loves  and 
fosters  in  them.  In  the  kingdom  of  God  the  true  and  eternal 
significance  of  marriage  will  be  preserved  and  will  endure — 
Christ  the  vvficjiLo^,  mankind  the  vv/j,(f)r)  (Eph.  v,  25-32; 
Matt,  xxii.-xxv. ;  John  iii.  29;  Eev.  xxi.  9,  xxii.  17).  So. 
with  the  family  ;  the  true  father  is  God  (Eph.  iii.  1 5).  In 
the  final  consummation  also,  science  will  for  the  first  time 
reach  her  perfect  form  when  faith  shall  have  passed  into 
sight  (1  Cor.  xiii.  9—12).  Then,  too,  will  the  idea  of  beauty 
celebrate  its  highest  triumphs,  for  nature  will  be  included 
in  the  universal  transfiguration.  Further,  as  the  perfected 
kingdom  of  God  is  portrayed  under  the  image  of  a  house  of 
God,  so  it  is  also  called  the  State  or  City  of  God,  because  that 
which  in  the  State  is  of  eternal  worth,  viz.  justice  and  good 
order,  will  be  preserved  and  manifested  in  it.  Finally,  and  as 
a  matter  of  course,  religious  fellowship  will  also  be  j)erfected 
in  the  final  consummation ;  and  that  not  merely  so  far  as 
individual  communion  with  God  is  concerned,  but  also  with 
reference  to  the  service  of  thanks  and  praise  which  the 
religious  community  renders  to  God.  Believers  made  perfect 
are  represented  as  7rav^jvpc<i,  as  an  assembly  holding  sacred 
festival  (Heb.  xii.  22  f . ;  Eev.  v.  9,  xxi.).  When  thus  the 
purpose  of  divine  love  has  been  realized,  God  will  be  all  in 
all  (1  Cor,  XV.  28).  This  does  not  mean  that  the  world  will 
lose  its  existence  in  God,  but  that  the  divine  will  and  the 
divine  life  will  permeate  all  things, — all  as  a  whole,  and  each 
individual  thing  according  to  its  nature, — and  will  bind  all 
things  together. 

Thus  the  attainment  of  the  world's  goal  is  a  work  which 
in  every  aspect  of  it  is  at  once  human  and  divine,  ©ela 
irdvra  koI  dvOpcoiriva  irdvra.  This  is  the  sum  of  the  whole 
matter — the  divine  OeXijfia,  in  the  whole  of  its  extent,  must 
become  the  OiXrj/jba  of  man  as  a  moral  being. 

The  foregoing  exposition  may  be  sufficient  to  show  that  the 
moral  law,  considered  in  its  contents,  or,  in  other  words,  the 
world's  ide?l,  is  not  an  abstract  barren  formula,  but  an  ideal 


298  §  32.    IDEALIZATION  OF  THE  MORAL  IDEAL. 

organism,  which  does  justice  to  what  is  individual  as  well  as 
to  wliat  is  common  to  all,  to  nature  as  well  as  to  mind,  and 
thereby  gains  for  itself  an  infinite  richness  of  contents.  More- 
over, the  divine  ideal  of  the  world  embraces  not  only  the  goal, 
but  also  the  road  which  leads  to  it. 


§  32.   The  Way  to  the  Realization  of  the  World's  Ideal. 

The  inward  inter-dependence  of  the  factors  which  constitute 
the  kingdom  of  God  must  be  reflected  in  the  moral 
process.  Hence  each  stage  in  this  process  must  be 
preceded  by  the  stage  which  forms  its  necessary  pre- 
supposition. And  this  holds  good  both  of  individuals 
and  of  the  race  as  a  whole.  Accordingly  the  physical 
conditions  described  in  §  10—17  along  with  the  natural 
communities  to  which  they  gave  rise,  pave  the  way  for 
the  entrance  of  the  consciousness  of  llight,  and  the  con- 
sequent formation  of  States.  With  the  consciousness  of 
right  the  legal  state  is  reached,  and  it  again  becomes  the 
preparation  for  the  stage  of  the  free,  moral  spirit,  the 
spirit  of  love,  which  finds  immediate  realization  in  the 
religious  community  of  the  Church. 

1.  At  the  present  day,  when  humanity  has  a  long  career 
of  moral  progress  stretching  behind  it,  all  the  moral  spheres 
exist  simultaneously,  and  reciprocally  condition  each  other. 
The  family,  for  example,  is  conditioned  by  the  State  and  the 
Church,  and  these  again  by  the  family,  so  that  it  is  difficult  to 
imagine  that  any  one  of  them  could  correspond  to  its  idea 
without  the  presence  and  co-operation  of  the  others.  In  that 
ideal  organism  which  is  the  goal  of  the  world  they  do  indeed 
appear  side  by  side,  though  each  of  them  has  its  own  jiarti- 
cular  jDrinciple.  Nevertheless,  it  has  not  always  been  so  as  a 
matter  of  actual  fact  from  the  time  that  humanity  began  to 
exist. 

Tliere  was  a  time  when,  to  say  nothing  of  science  and  art, 
there  was  no  Church,  and  farther  back  when  there  was  no 
State.  Tliis  earlier  period  we  must  designate  as  of  necessity 
morally  imperfect,  but  it  does  not  follow  that  it  was   sinful. 


NECESSARY  SUCCESSION  OF  STAGES.  290 

On  the  contrary,  if  we  examine  the  ideas  underlying  the 
various  moral  spheres,  and  thus  see  how  the  relations  sub- 
sisting between  them  arise,  it  will  become  evident  that  the 
Ideal  or  World-goal,  which  embraces  at  one  and  the  same 
time  all  the  factors  which  constitute  the  moral  organism, 
cannot  come  into  existence  by  a  stroke  of  magic,  but  must  of 
necessity  have  a  gradual  growth,  one  factor  being  mediated 
through  another.  And  our  present  investigation  has  a  signifi- 
cance for  all  times ;  because  none  of  the  departments  of 
moral  life  are  in  existence  once-  for  all,  but  must  be  main- 
tained through  a  process  of  constant  reproduction.  Further, 
since  each  of  them  has  the  tendency  to  make  itself,  as  far  as 
it  can,  a  complete  whole  or  centre,  it  is  instructive  to  see 
how  its  perfection  is  conditioned  by  the  presence  of  the  others. 
jSTow  the  gradual  process  of  which  we  have  spoken  is  not  to 
be  conceived  as  if  it  meant  that  all  the  various  spheres  existed 
together  from  the  beginning,  thougli  in  an  imperfect  shape. 
For  example,  it  is  only  after  the  spread  of  family  life  that  the 
State  can  come  into  existence  at  all ;  the  State  again  is  a 
preparation  for  the  Church,  for  it  is  the  school  in  which  man 
is  trained  in  the  idea  of  right — an  idea  to  which  we  were 
previously  brought  by  the  doctrine  of  the  law,  and  which,  as 
was  shown  in  §  2  3,  has  its  origin  in  God.  It  is  true  that  the 
moral  capacities  for  these  spheres  arc  present  from  the  begin- 
ning and  are  not  inoperative.  But  in  order  that  they  may 
attain  to  full  realization,  whatever  is  a  necessary  condition  of 
any  stage  of  progress  must  take  precedence  of  it  in  time.  It 
is  quite  consistent  with  this  truth  (inasmuch  as  the  good  is  a 
unity),  that  whatever  comes  earlier  and  as  a  condition  of  a 
subsequent  stage,  is  in  another  aspect  itself  conditioned  by 
what  follows,  since  it  is  only  in  connection  with  the  latter 
that  it  attains  its  perfect  form. 

2.  With  regard,  therefore,  both  to  individuals  and  com- 
munities, the  typical  form  of  this  succession  of  moral  stages 
is  as  follows.  The  third  stage,  that  of  the  conscious  union 
of  the  free  and  the  morally  necessary,  must  be  preceded 
by  a  stage  of  which  the  characteristic  is  law  in  the  form 
of  command.  Again,  the  stage  of  law,  since  it  cannot 
begin  with  the  first  breath  of  man,  must  be  preceded  by 
that  state  of  existence  in   which  man  is  an  immediate  but 


300       §  32.    EEALIZATION  OF  THE  MORAL  IDEAL.      SYNOPSIS. 

unstable  unity  of  human  powers.  Moreover,  as  it  was  not 
sin  that  brought  this  sequence  of  stages  into  existence,  so 
sin  cannot  annul  it :  it  belongs  to  the  original  form  of  the 
moral  process  in  general.  Accordingly  there  must  be  (1) 
a  life  heforc  the  law ;   (2)  under  the  law ;  (3)  in  the  law. 

3.  We  have  already  treated  of  the  life  hcfore  the  law  in  the 
third  section  of  the  First  Division  (§  17,  18).  There,  those 
natural  organizations  were  considered  which  arise  of  them- 
selves, and  apart  from  the  moral  law,  out  of  the  conditions  of 
nature  both  physical  and  psychical.  We  have  seen  what 
progress  can  be  made  by  individuals  and  communities  under 
these  conditions  alone,  and  also  wherein  they  are  still  im- 
perfect. It  therefore  remains  for  us,  in  tracing  through  an 
ascending  series  the  development  of  the  contents  of  the  diXTj/jia. 
Oeov  or  divine  World-ideal,  to  examine  the  other  two  stages 
embraced  by  this  ideal  organism — viz.  the  stage  of  right  and 
that  of  the  free  moral  spirit  or  of  love.^  We  have  thus  to 
consider — 

I.  In  what  respects  the  entrance  of  the  idea  of  right  or  of 
the  law  promotes  the  realization  of  the  good.  This  has 
reference  both  to  individuals  and  communities. 

II.  The  imperfection  of  the  legal  standpoint. 

(1)  Apart  altogether  from  sin. 

(2)  When  sin  has  appeared  (Ethical  Ponerology). 
This  will  lead  us  to  inquire — 

III.  What  it  is  that  is  still  requisite  for  the  perfect  realiza- 
tion of  the  moral  principle ;  or  in  other  words,  what  it  is  that 
is  still  requisite  in  order  to  make  it  possible  for  individuals, 
communities,  and  the  world  as  a  whole  to  reach  a  condition 
in  which  moral  imperfection  will  no  longer  be  a  necessity. 

Or  shortly  ;  we  have  to  consider — 

I.  The  stage  of  right. 

II.  Its  imperfection.     This  carries  us  forward  to — 

III.  The  stage  of  love  or  of  the  gospel ;  the  gospel  which 
was  in  the  OeXTj^ia  Oeov  he/ore  the  foundation  of  the  world, 
and  was  therefore  present  when  its  foundations  were  laid. 

J^ote. — The  lower  stages  continue  to  exist  as  substructure : 
tlie  higher  stages  do  not  abolish,  but  supplement  and  complete 
them. 

'  Cf.  besides,  §  20.  2,  with  §  23,  p.  224,  note  ;  §  25,  §  30.  3. 


§  33.    ABSOLUTE  SPHERE  OF  EIGHT.  301 

FIEST    SECTIOK 

THE  STAGE  OF  LAW,  OR  OF  RIGHT. 

§  33,   The  Absolute  Sphere  of  Bight,  or  the  Relations  hetiuccn 
God  and  Man. 

[Cf.  supra,  §  7.  4  and  5,  §  20-23.      System  of  Christian 
Doctrine,  vol.  i.  §  23,  24. — Ed.] 

The  entrance  of  the  consciousness  of  Absohite  Law  forms  a 
great  step  in  advance,  especially  as  it  is  united  in  the 
closest  possible  way  with  the  religious  feeling  of  depend- 
ence upon  God.  This  feeling  now  comes  to  fuller 
maturity  ;  for  our  dependence  upon  God  is  recognised  to 
be  a  moral  dependence.  Also,  the  idea  of  God  itself  is 
ethically  determined,  as  the  idea  of  the  Holy  and  Just 
One.  Hence  the  distinction  between  God  and  man  is 
more  completely  carried  out.  Further,  as  a  morally 
responsible  being,  man  is  now  invested  with  freedom  or 
the  power  of  moral  choice,  and  with  the  dignity  of  moral 
determination  (§  19). 

1.  The  legal  stage  forms  a  great  advance  upon  mere 
€ud?emonism  (§  18).  For  now,  man  knows  God  as  Lawgiver 
and  Judge,  and  (what  is  the  converse  of  this)  he  is  conscious 
of  his  own  obligation  and  responsibility.  The  idea  of  duty 
also  establishes  man  in  his  rights  as  a  moral  being  (§  23); 
and  in  accordance  with  the  idea  of  right,  God  and  man  stand 
related  to  each  other  as  distinct  beings,  each  with  his  own 
rights,  although  this  relation  is  not  one  of  co-ordination.  The 
law  proclaims  that  man  is  free.  He  is  free  with  respect  to 
nature ;  he  is  independent  even  with  regard  to  God, — though 
it  is  through  God  that  he  is  so — in  so  far  as  God  cannot 
compel  him  to  what  is  good,  and  cannot  effect  any  ethical 
good  in  human  life  without  the  co-operation  of  man.  It  is 
no  wonder  that  with  the  law  a  higher  self-consciousness,  a 
nobler  sense  of  life  is  awakened,  since  man  now  becomes 
aware  that  a  good  of  infinite  value  has  been  committed  to  his 
charge.     Thus  it  is  quite  conceivable  how  the  Eabbis,  contrast- 


302  §  33.    ABSOLUTE  SPHERE  OF  RIGHT. 

ing  the  position  of  the  heathen  world  with  the  position  of 
those  who  had  received  the  gift  of  the  Old  Testament,  believed 
they  were  justified  in  calling  the  standpoint  of  the  law  a 
"  n^m  nsnn  "  a  new  creation. 

T    T-:         T      ■  :  ' 

It  is  no  doubt  true  that  the  advance  which  has  been  made 
is  at  first  only  an  advance  in  knowledge.  On  the  stage  of 
right,  the  law  is  set  over  against  the  impulses  and  the  will, 
but  it  has  not  as  yet  gained  an  entrance  into  the  will.  On 
the  contrary,  transgression  is  now  for  the  first  time  made 
possible,  and  will  become  actual  if  this  mere  external  relation 
between  God  and  man  remains  unsurpassed.  Nevertheless, 
were  it  lut  for  the  legal  stage  and  the  relative  independence 
of  man  that  comes  with  it,  a  moral  union  of  the  necessary 
and  the  free  would  be  impossible  (§  30).  At  the  most  there 
would  only  be  a  physical  union.  For  did  the  divine  will 
simply  pour  in  upon  the  human  as  an  irresistible  power, 
without  first  confronting  the  human  will  in  the  form  of  obli- 
gation and  demand,  then  loving  self-communication  on  the 
part  of  God  would  sink  to  the  level  of  a  mere  physical  force.^ 
For  it  would  lack  the  mediation  of  the  demands  of  the  law, 
at  least  of  the  law  as  requiring  faith  or  receptivity  on  the 
part  of  man.  The  legal  stage,  therefore,  whether  long  or 
short,  cannot  be  overleaped :  it  forms,  even  apart  from  sin 
(and  consequently,  even  in  the  case  of  the  first  man),  an 
indispensable  factor.  It  is  often  indeed  confounded  with  a 
state  of  sinfulness ;  but  neither  does  the  law  give  rise  to  sin, 
nor  sin  to  the  law.  The  mere  fact  that  the  demands  of  the 
law  have  "  not  yet  been  fulfilled  "  is  not  sin  ;  for  if  it  were, 
then  the  law  could  not  by  itself  be  an  essential  factor  in 
human  progress.  It  would,  in  fact,  be  a  contradiction ;  for 
previous  to  the  legal  stage,  it  would  be  both  absolute  and  yet 
of  necessity  unfulfilled.  The  two  forms  taken  by  the  divine 
activity — the  creative  and  the  legislative,  voluntas  and  pra^- 
ceptum — could  never  be  separated,  but  would  have  to  remain 
blended  in  absolute  identity.  Sin  arises  when  the  fulfilment 
of  the  law  is  delayed,  although  it  can  and  ought  to  take  place  ; 
and  the  cause  of  such  delay  can  only  lie  in  the  abnormal 
resistance  of  a  will  opposed  to  the  will  of  God  in  the  law. 

^  [Of  course  this  does  not  exclude  the  fact  that  the  law,  too,  must  find  a  point 
of  contact  in  the  nature  of  man.     Cf.  p.  140. — Ed.] 


§  33rt.    SECONDARY  SPHEEE  OF  EIGHT.  303 

But  heforc  the  law  is  fulfilled,  its  demands  must  be  presented, 
and  thus  a  knowledge  of  it  given,  a  knowledge  which 
addresses  itself  to  the  will. 

§  33«.   The  Secondary  Sphere  of  Bight. 

The  consciousness  of  the  absolute  sphere  of  Eight,  or  of  the 
law  of  God,  gives  rise  to  a  Secondary  Sphere  of  Right. 
Since  the  consciousness  of  divine  right  or  of  justice 
makes  out  of  the  mere  human  individual  a  person 
endowed  with  rights,  it  sets  up  in  opposition  to  self-will 
a  sacred  standard  of  action,  which  raises  communities 
constructed  on  a  merely  natural  basis  out  of  their 
eudsemonistic  form,  and  gives  them  a  moral  shape. 
Thus,  when  the  idea  of  absolute  right  or  objective  divine 
right  is  recognised  by  man  as  of  binding  authority,  it 
gives  rise  to  human  relations  of  a  higher  kind ;  what 
we  possess  becomes  our  property ;  sexual  association 
becomes  marriage ;  proles  or  offspring  becomes  a  family ; 
and  the  mere  mass  of  a  nation  becomes  a  State.  And 
it  is  a  moral  duty  to  discover  more  and  more  fully  this 
objective  right  which  resides  in  the  divinely  appointed 
nature  of  things. 

[Kant,  Bcchtslehre.  Hegel,  Rcchtsphilosophic.  Herbart,  Prak- 
tische  Philosophic,  Werke,  vol.  viii.  pp.  78  sq.,  101  sq.,  134  sq. ; 
vol.  ii.  pp.  132  sq. ;  cf.  also  his  analytical  examination  of 
Naturrecht  and  Morcd,  vol.  viii.  Stahl,  Die  Philosophic  des 
Pechts.  Savigny,  Ucher  den  Beruf  unserer  Zeit  zur  Gesetzge- 
hung  unci  Bechtswisscnschaft.  Rothe,  Ethik,  2nd  ed.  vol.  ii. 
p.  204  sq.  Chalybiius,  System  der  speculativen  Ethik,  vol.  ii. 
I.  H.  richte,  Die  p)hilosophischen  Lehren  vom  Becht,  Stacd,  Sitte. 
Trendelenburg,  Naturrecht.  Baumann,  Hanclbuch  der  Moral 
nehst  einem  Abriss  der  Bechtsphilosophie.  Schuppe,  Grundzuge 
der  Ethik.  Dahn,  Bechtsphilosophisehe  Studien.  Kostlin,  Staat, 
Becht  und  Kirche  in  der  evangelischcn  Ethik.  Sttulien  unci 
Kritiken,  1877.  Ihering,  Kampf  tons  Becht.  Hartmanu, 
Phdnomenologie  des  sittlichen  Bewusstseins,  p.  496  sq.  For 
additional  literature,  vid.  Part  II.,  Division  3,  Section  2,  The 
Doctrine  of  the  State. — Ed.-] 

1.  The  idea  of  absolute  right   gives   rise  to  a  secondary 


304      §  33a.    SECONDAEY  SPHEEE  OF  RIGHT.      COMMUNITIES. 

sphere  of  right,  a  system  of  moral  relations  based  upon  right, 
subsisting  between  man  and  man.  We  have  already  discussed 
this  subject  in  §  23.  The  idea  of  right  and  duty  distin- 
guishes and  separates  men  from  each  other,  but  yet  in  such 
a  manner  that  by  means  of  it  they  are  brought  into  a  more 
enduring  connection  than  the  merely  natural  one.  To  the 
right  of  one  man  there  corresponds  the  duty  of  another,  and 
the  objective  law  of  justice  establishes  and  confirms  the  rights 
and  duties  of  all  alike,  since  it  lays  its  behests  equally  upon 
all.  Objective  right  or  law  makes  all  men  objects  of  respect 
for  one  another.  For  it  makes  all  men  its  organs,  in  whom 
it  is  designed  to  assume  a  personal  form  in  the  world,  and 
thus  in  a  certain  measure  confers  dignity  upon  all.  Hence 
the  standpoint  of  right  effects  two  things  at  one  and  the  same 
time  ;  it  places  men  in  a  position  of  independence  over  against 
each  other,  and  it  also  brings  them  together  into  a  relation  in 
which  there  is  an  absolute  bond  of  connection  between  them 
— a  relation  higher  than  the  mere  physical  ones,  which  rest 
upon  utility,  prudence,  and  caprice,  higher  even  than  that 
produced  by  the  sense  of  universal  human  affinity  itself.  It 
is  now  seen  to  be  a  duty  to  uphold  universal  right,  embracing 
and  regulating,  as  it  clearly  does,  all  human  relationships. 

2.  Communities.  By  means  of  the  law  we  become  con- 
scious that  it  is  our  duty  to  recognise  and  respect  the  honour 
of  our  fellow-men,  both  in  its  physical  and  moral  aspects. 
And  hence  individual  communities  gain  a  higher  import  and 
value.  All  of  these,  indeed,  have  their  origin  in  human 
nature  and  natural  impulse,  and  existed  in  rudimentary  forms 
(§  17.  3)  before  ever  the  consciousness  of  law  arose.  But 
now  law  clothes  them  with  higher  than  merely  physical, 
with  divine  rights.  Having  their  basis  in  the  constitution 
of  human  nature,  they  are  the  expression  of  the  divine  will, 
and  demand  to  be  treated  and  conducted  in  accordance  with 
their  essential  nature.  And  now  on  the  stage  of  law,  full 
recognition  is  given  to  their  divine  rights,  to  their  sanctity 
and  inviolability.     This  holds  good 

(a)  With  respect  to  sexual  association,  which  now  rests 
upon  the  consciousness  of  the  essential  equality  of  the  rights 
of  husband  and  wife,  so  that  on  neither  side  do  we  find 
rights   dissociated   from    duties.      Neither    caprice,   nor  self- 


FAMILY.       SOCIETY.       THE  STATE.  305 

seeking,  nor  desire  must  be  made  the  ground  of  an  alliance 
between  the  sexes,  or  the  cause  of  its  dissolution ;  for  then 
each  member  of  it  would  become  merely  a  means  with  regard 
to  the  other,  and  would  not  be  recognised  as  an  end  in  him- 
self. For  this  very  reason,  a  union  based  on  duty  is  more 
lasting  than  one  that  arises  out  of  finite  interests  ;  for  duty 
endures  when  finite  interests  give  way.  It  is  only  an  alliance 
of  this  kind,  consciously  based  upon  duty  and  the  law  of  God, 
and  existing  under  the  protection  of  that  law,  that  deserves  to 
he  eallecl  marriage.  Nay  more,  wherever  the  essential  equality 
of  the  rights  of  husband  and  wife  is  recognised,  the  necessary 
result  is  that  marriage  takes  the  form  of  monogamy,  and  is 
contracted  for  life. 

{]))  The  consciousness  of  the  protection  which  right  throws 
over  the  personal  life  also  elevates  the  offspring  of  sexual 
association  — proles  —  into  the  family.  Procreation  now 
involves  the  duty  of  educating  or  developing  the  personality 
that  is  produced. 

(c)  Social  intereourse  also  receives  a  higher  form,  since 
men  now  mutually  respect  each  other's  rights.  By  means  of 
justitia  commutativa  their  dealings  with  each  other  become 
much  more  widely  extended,  and  much  more  safe.  To  fulfil 
agreements  is  now  known  to  be  a  duty  imposed  by  right. 

(d)  But  the  most  important  and  peculiar  creation  of  the 
consciousness  of  objective  right  or  law  is  that  community 
which  comprehends  all  those  that  have  been  named,  and 
which  has  for  its  function  the  protection  of  their  rights  as 
well  as  the  rights  of  individuals.  This  community  arises  in 
the  following  manner.  Families  multiply  and  spread  out 
into  tribes  and  national  masses,  and  then  these  are  brought 
together  and  united  into  a  i^ullic  instittUion  for  the  mainten- 
ance of  right.  This  is  the  beginning  of  the  State.  A  mere 
multitude  of  families  and  tribes  cannot  in  itself  form  a  State ; 
it  is  only  the  material  out  of  which  a  State  is  made,  it 
needs  the  idea  of  right  to  give  it  life.  Further,  as  the  State 
is  not  produced  by  mere  physical  means,  as  it  is  not  the 
product  of  physical  force  or  of  the  mechanical  power  of 
numbers,  so,  too,  it  does  not  owe  its  existence  to  caprice  or 
contract  alone.  Xor  do  we  as  yet  have  a  State  where  merely 
certain  prudent,  useful  rules  and  established  rights  (as  matters 

u 


306        §  33«..    SECONDARY  SPHERE  OF  RIGHT.       THE  STATE. 

of  custom  it  may  be)  have  arisen  in  connection  with  pro- 
perty and  the  family.  The  State  exists  only  where  the 
interest  in  right  has  become  so  energetic  that  a  new  form  of 
community  appears,  embracing  all  those  earlier  ones, — a  com- 
munity instituted  to  protect  right,  to  carry  it  into  execution 
with  regard  to  all,  and  to  defend  all  against  injury,  whether 
done  wilfully  or  through  ignorance.  Right  as  universal  will — 
the  will,  that  is,  that  right  be  administered  everywhere — is 
outwardly  realized  in  a  special  organization,  viz.  constif,uted 
anjthority.  Right  is  for  all ;  it  has  to  protect  all  against 
injury.  As  merely  finite  indeed,  the  individual  person  could 
have  no  absolute  claim  to  such  protection.  But  he  stands 
in  essential  relation  to  morality ;  he  exists  for  moral  ends, 
and  is  the  necessary  organ  of  morality.  Thus  in  protecting 
him  right  protects  morality  itself,  and  for  this  reason  it 
secures  for  him  the  rights  and  the  respect  which  are  his 
due.  The  aim  of  the  administration  of  justice,  therefore, 
is  to  defend  the  freedom  of  the  personality ;  the  freedom, 
that  is,  which  the  individual  must  have  in  order  to  render 
his  moral  development  possible.  It  is  the  duty  of  the  State 
to  ensure  the  possibility  of  the  real  freedom,  i.e.  of  the 
harmonious  moral  development  of  the  personality.  Thus  the 
order  established  for  the  maintenance  of  right  is  the  bulwarlc 
which  makes  it  possible  for  man  to  give  free  exercise  to  his 
spiritual  powers  in  all  the  moral  spheres  of  life.  This 
order,  exhibited  in  the  State,  is  the  sacred  basis  upon  which 
the  whole  moral  world  rests ;  it  is  the  negative  condition  of 
all  morality,  and  is  therefore  indispensable  if  there  is  to  be 
a  moral  world  at  all.  It  must,  therefore,  should  occasion 
demand,  be  enforced  and  upheld  by  physical  means  or  com- 
pulsion. It  is  the  necessary  outcome  of  the  moral  idea  itself, 
the  negative  side  of  its  manifestation.  Since  the  ethical  idea 
of  right  has  recourse  to  physical  compulsion,  and  therefore  to 
nature,  for  the  attainment  of  its  ends,  it  assumes  the  form 
of  physical  necessity. 

3.  The  Right  of  Punishment.  Wherever,  then,  either  the 
community  as  a  whole,  or  its  leaders,  have  become  conscious 
of  right  as  absolutely  valid  and  necessary,  it  is  the  duty 
of  all  not  only  to  subordinate  themselves  individually  and 
separately  to  objective  law,  but  also  to  feel  themselves  bound. 


EIGHT  OF  PUNISHMENT.  307 

as  one  man,  to  become  the  organs  of  the  idea  of  right.  And 
since  this  idea  represents  a  good  of  absolute  value,  all  that 
exists  must  be  at  its  service,  for  the  purpose  of  upholding 
right  upon  the  earth.  This  holds  good  even  with  regard 
to  the  transgressor.  Him  it  confronts  with  punishment,  and 
it  arms  the  members  of  the  commonwealth  with  the  power 
to  inflict  it  (Gen.  ix.  6  ;  Ex.  xxi.  22  ;  Eom.  xiii.  1  ff.). 

It  is  the  right  and  duty  of  the  State  to  carry  right  into  effect, 
even  by  external  force.  Justice  is  a  good  of  absolute  worth, 
and  it  must  be  defended  before  the  other  moral  excellences 
which  belong  to  the  personality  can  possibly  exist  at  all.  All 
men  are  bound  to  place  themselves,  in  life  and  limb,  at  the 
service  of  this  idea,  as  its  organs  or  the  means  which  it 
employs,  and  thus  to  uphold  the  validity  of  justice  as  the 
honour  and  soul  of  the  State.  All,  too,  are  bound  to  conform 
themselves  to  the  general  will  of  the  community  that  justice 
be  carried  out ;  and  more  particularly,  they  must  undergo 
punishment  when  they  have  done  violence  to  right,  in  order 
that  the  injury  inflicted  may  be  atoned  for,  and  the  majesty 
of  right  vindicated.  It  is  true  that  if  we  do  not  start  from 
an  objective  law,  from  a  divine  right  which  demands  uncon- 
ditionally that  justice  be  done,  if,  on  the  contrary,  we  start 
from  freedom  instead  of  from  duty,  and  derive  the  right  to 
inflict  punishment  from  convention  only,  or  at  least  from  tacit 
consent — then  the  question  must  arise,  How  do  men  come  to 
have  the  power  of  punishing  other  men,  even  to  the  extent 
of  putting  them  to  death  ?  Is  it  not  a  usurpation  of  divine 
rights,  when  men  sit  in  judgment  upon  their  fellow-men  and 
bring  them  to  account,  without  even  getting  their  consent  by 
means  of  a  formal  agreement  ?  It  is  certainly  the  case  that 
the  exercise  of  the  power  of  punishment  has  no  right  to 
take  place,  unless  it  can  be  shown  to  be  a  duty,  a  service 
which  we  owe  to  justice.  But  such  in  fact  it  is.  It  is 
undeniable  that  if  there  be  an  objective  law,  imposing  objec- 
tive, absolute  obligations,  then  a  violation  of  right  deserves 
punishment  and  incurs  it.  Divine  justice  would  be  some- 
thing else  than  it  is,  it  would  not  be  in  earnest  with  itself,  if 
it  failed  to  take  a  punitive  attitude  with  regard  to  a  violation 
of  the  law,  and  w^ere  therefore  wholly  indifferent  to  it. 

When  once  the  idea  of  justice  has  been  awakened  among 


308  §  33a.    SECONDARY  SPHERE  OF  RIGHT. 

men,  and  men  have  surrendered  themselves  to  it  to  be  the 
organs  and  means  which  it  employs,  when  they  have  staked 
everything  upon  the  preservation  of  justice  as  the  primary  con- 
dition of  the  moral  existence  of  human  society, — then,  without 
fail,  this  zeal  which  is  employed  in  the  service  of  justice  must 
carry  into  effect  what  justice  demands,  must  therefore  restore 
its  authority  when  that  has  been  shaken  by  a  breach  of  right, 
and  consequently  must  inflict  punishment  upon  the  evil-doer. 
For  when  a  negation  of  right  has  been  caused  by  a  lawless 
will,  dangerous  to  society,  the  latter  has  not  simply  to  be 
rendered  harmless,  even  though  it  be  by  physical  compulsion. 
The  criminal  must  not  merely  be  treated  as  a  being  in  a  state 
of  nature,  and  brought  into  order  by  natural  force.  He  must 
have  a  sentence  passed  upon  him,  in  which  some  positive  evil 
is  connected  with  the  offence  he  has  committed,  as  a  just 
expression  of  resentment  against  his  guilt.  Ho  would  not  be 
treated  justly,  in  fact,  if  he  were  treated  simply  as  a  natural 
being,  and  merely  rendered  harmless,  as  if  he  were  a  wild 
animal.  On  the  contrary,  he  is  no  mere  creature  of  nature, 
but  a  man,  and  therefore  the  just  stroke  that  falls  upon  him 
must  be  something  more  than  a  mere  physical  occurrence.  It 
must  be  delivered  for  the  sake  of  justice  and  out  of  zeal  for 
it,  since  even  in  the  transgressor  justice  sees  one  who  was 
intended  to  be  its  organ,  and  who  is  therefore  responsible  for 
his  misdeed.  And  an  evil  inflicted  upon  the  author  of  a  wrong, 
from  motives  of  justice  and  for  the  ends  of  justice,  is  called 
punishment. 

Now,  wherever  there  is  no  ijolitical  organization  for  the 
administration  of  justice  by  means  of  constituted  authority, 
self-defence  is  the  only  means  left  of  protecting  one's  individual 
rights,  while  the  protection  and  security  of  society  depend  en- 
tirely upon  the  private  administration  of  justice,  such  as  is  seen 
in  Mood-revenge,  in  lynch  laio,  and  in  the  secret  Vchme.  But  it  is 
manifest  what  a  sorry  equipment  justice  has,  where  the  accuser, 
or  perhaps  even  the  injured  person  himself,  is  in  addition  both 
judge  and  executioner.  For  in  such  circumstances  the  passion 
for  revenge  is  almost  sure  to  lead  to  injustice.  Thus,  in  order 
that  justice  may  be  preserved,  it  is  necessary  that  the  functions 
of  prosecutor  and  judge  be  separated,  and  it  is  no  less  necessary 
that  the  judge   be  removed  above   every  private,   subjective 


EIGHT  OF  PUNISHMENT,  309 

emotion  and  passion.  The  administration  of  justice  is,  accord- 
ing to  its  fundamental  idea,  a  matter  which  is  the  common 
concern  of  all,  a  public  affair,  just  as  the  injury  which 
happened  to  one  affects  all  together  with  him.  It  is  not  only 
that  their  interests  and  security  are  affected  by  it,  but  apart 
from  this,  it  is  the  interest  and  duty  of  all  to  be  answerable, 
in  their  own  way,  for  the  authority  of  justice  upon  earth. 
And  just  because  it  is  a  matter  pertaining  to  all,  no  one  must 
treat  it  as  if  it  were  a  private  affair,  and  arbitrarily  make  it 
his  own  particular  concern.  On  the  contrary,  since  it  is  of  the 
essence  of  right  to  seek  to  become  truly  the  will  of  the  whole 
community,  this  must  appear  in  the  form  whicli  the  administra- 
tion of  justice  takes.  The  administration  of  justice  must 
appear  as  a  universal,  public,  and  not  as  a  mere  private 
concern  ;  the  matters  it  deals  with  affect  not  only  the  rights  of 
individuals  but  the  rights  of  the  community  as  a  whole,  and 
hence  it  must  be  carried  out  iii  the  name  of  the  whole  com- 
onunity.  It  must  be  raised  above  and  made  independent  of  all 
parties,  in  order  that  it  may  serve  the  ends  of  justice  alone. 

From  the  same  point  of  view  it  is  also  clear  that  wherever 
the  consciousness  of  right  exists,  while  at  the  same  time  there 
is  as  yet  no  political  organization  for  the  maintenance  of  right, 
it  is  a  matter  of  duty  and  of  moral  necessity  that  all  should 
assist  in  laying  the  Ibundations  of  a  State ;  since  this  is  the 
first  thing  that  must  be  done  if  society  is  to  assume  a  form 
which  is  worthy  of  human  beings.  No  less  is  it  a  moral  duty, 
one,  too,  which  may  be  enforced,  or  a  duty  imposed  by  right, 
that  all  who  are  within  the  State  should  belong  to  it.  The 
State  now  throws  the  protection  of  justice  round  tke  individual, 
his  house  and  proj)erty,  and  round  marriage  and  family  life ; 
it  is  now  a  public  matter,  in  which  the  whole  community  is 
concerned,  to  see  that  the  rights  of  all  are  protected. 

We  have  seen  (§  17.  2)  that  the  idea  of  right,  which  comes 
to  realization  in  the  State,  turns  what  any  one  is  possessed  of 
into  his  property.  In  like  manner,  a  people  by  becoming  a 
State  enters  upon  a  possession  that  belongs  to  the  whole 
nation,  a  possession  which  has  an  external  form  but  has  also 
a  spiritual  significance — in  other  words,  a  fatherland.  This 
forms  its  earthly  body  as  it  were,  which  it  may  not  allow  to 
fall  to  pieces  or  be  taken   from  it  by  force,  but  which  it  is 


310        §  33a.    SECONDARY  SPHERE  OF  RIGHT.       THE  STATE. 

bound  to  maintain  and  defend  on  behalf  of  tlie  great  moral 
personality  of  the  State,  just  as  it  is  the  duty  of  every 
individual  to  care  for  and  protect  his  own  body. 

The  State  gives  free  scope  to  the  individual  in  the  exercise 
of  his  various  activities  ;  its  law  protects  and  promotes  the 
free  development  of  his  personality,  by  securing  it  against  any 
attempt  to  arrest  it.  Thus  all  the  various  kinds  of  individual 
traits  and  talents  move  and  act  freely  within  the  State ;  it 
prevents  their  collision,  or  renders  such  collision  harmless,  by 
repairiug  any  injury  that  is  done  to  right;  and  so,  in  its  own 
way,  it  contributes  to  the  solution  of  the  moral  problem  that  is 
set  before  mankind. 

Contempt  for  the  State  is  frequently  exhibited  by  false 
religious  enthusiasm  (the  Anabaptists),  or  when  the  Church  sets 
itself  up  as  a  rival  political  institution  (Ifoman  Catholicism). 

Note. — Friend sliip,  Science,  and  Art  on  the  stage  of  Right. — 
Friendship  is  not  directly  affected  by  the  idea  of  right,  inasmuch 
as  right  is  what  is  universally  valid,  what  is  the  same  every- 
where, whereas  the  formation  of  friendships  rests  primarily  upon 
special  and  individual  grounds.  Nevertlieless,  in  so  far  as 
friendship  unallied  with  respect  is  mere  trifling,  or  is  no  more 
than  comradeship,  the  idea  of  right  ennobles  this  relation  too. 
By  means  of  the  idea  of  right  and  the  new  spheres  of  life  which 
it  creates.  Science  gains  fresh  regions  for  her  activity.  Never- 
theless, it  is  not  an  accidental  circumstance  that  Science  and 
Art  did  not  flourish  in  the  two  nations  which  were  the 
representatives  of  the  idea  of  right  in  pre-Christian  times. 
These  were  the  Helirews  and  tlie  liomans,  who  represented  it  in 
opposite  ways — the  one  in  a  theocratic,  the  other  in  a  secular 
form.  Eight  is  the  standpoint  of  keenly  intelligent,  practical 
discernment.  It  is  prosaic,  it  nmst  not  depend  upon  fancy, 
feeling,  or  ideal  apperceptions.  Consequently  it  was  not  until 
these  nations  began  to  decline  that  either  of  them  showed  any 
appreciation  or  productive  capacity  with  regard  to  Art  and 
Science.  Neither  is  there  room  for  a  Church  at  this  stage, 
although  the  great  political  and  theocratic  lawgivers,  in  the 
sacerdotal  and  secular  States,  were  fully  aware  of  the  connection 
that  subsists  between  human  law  aird  religion  or  the  eternal, 
unwritten  laws.  Previous  to  Christianity,  the  religious  spirit, 
the  spirit  of  mutual  fellowship  between  God  and  man,  was  not 
so  powerful  in  the  world  as  to  form  a  specicd  religious  com- 
munity distinct  from  the  State.  Judaism  as  it  exists  at  present, 
in  which  every  vestige  of  a  State  has  disappeared,  is  no  proof 


IMPEKFECTION  OF  THE  STAGE  OF  LAW.  311 

to  the  contrary.  For  it  is  the  ruins  of  the  Theocracy ;  in  its 
nature  it  seeks  to  be  and  hopes  to  become  a  theocracy,  and  it  is 
this  hope  alone  which  keeps  it  alive.  It  was  only  by  force  that 
this  religion  was  separated  from  the  State ;  in  its  essential 
nature,  therefore,  this  separation  has  never  taken  place. 


SECOND    SECTION". 

THE  IMPERFECTION   OF  THE  STAGE  OF  LAW  OR  OF  RIGHT. 

CHAPTEE    FIEST. 

APART    FRO:\I    SIX. 

§34. 

Even  apart  from  corruptions  which  may  arise,  and  which 
the  law  cannot  prevent,  the  legal  stage,  considered  by 
itself,  is  an  essentially  imperfect  one,  with  reference 
both  to  the  absolute  and  the  secondary  spheres.  Wlien 
the  normal  moral  development  of  mankind  has  reached 
the  legal  stage,  the  desire  must  arise  for  a  higher 
communication  on  the  part  of  God  than  what  is  given 
in  creation  and  in  the  law ;  and  in  like  manner  the 
divine  love  is  not  content  with  the  mere  revelation  of 
law  in  the  form  of  demand,  even  should  it  be  love  tliat 
is  demanded ;  it  is  only  satisfied  when  it  reveals  itself 
in  the  hcstoival  of  love. 

1.  The  imperfection  of  the  legal  standpoint  with  relation 
to  God  is  obvious,  even  apart  from  sin,  from  several  points 
of  view.  On  the  stage  of  right  there  is  a  necessary  separation 
between  knowing  and  being ;  man  has  a  knowledge  of  the  law, 
but  what  he  knoivs  and  what  he  is  remain,  as  yet,  apart  from 
each  other.  Now  it  might  be  supposed  that  this  separation 
could  only  last  for  a  moment ;  that  the  will  would  immediately, 
and  as  a  normal  consequence,  fulfil  the  demand  that  is  addressed 
to  it,  and  thus  return  into  perfect  union  with  God.  But  the 
attainment  of  perfect  knowledge  is  itself  a  moral  problem  that 


312  §  34.   IMPERFECTION  OF  THE  STAGE  OF  LAW  IN 

can  only  be  solved  by  degrees ;  with  each  advance  in  know- 
ledge, therefore,  new  demands  present  themselves,  and  a  new 
separation  takes  place  between  what  ought  to  be  and  what 
is,  between  knowing  and  willing.  As  moral  knowledge 
increases,  it  penetrates  ever  deeper  and  deeper  into  the  connec- 
tions in  which  the  individual  himself  is  placed,  and  into  the 
wisdom  and  goodness  of  God.  Therefore,  although  the  will 
should  immediately  take  up  into  itself  the  precept  which  the 
intelligence  has  discerned,  still  the  stage  of  law  is  not  yet 
surpassed.  On  the  contrary,  since  knowledge  increases  gradu- 
ally, the  separation  between  knowing  and  willing  is  always 
renewed,  even  if  it  be  but  for  a  moment.  In  the  normal 
development  of  the  will,  again,  it  is  necessary  that  obedience^ 
— which  may  have  a  moral  import,  even  when  it  is  nothing  but 
simple  piety,  and  is  without  any  insight  into  the  inward  good- 
ness of  the  command  that  is  obeyed, — that  obedience  should 
grow  into  joyful  pleasure  in  and  love  to  the  good,  as  the  good 
becomes  more  and  more  clearly  known. 

2.  In  addition  to  this,  the  stage  of  law  cannot  prevent  sin. 
On  the  contrary,  it  gives  rise  to  temptation ;  for  it  recognises 
man's  independence  even  with  respect  to  God,  and  arouses 
in  him  the  sense  of  freedom.  If  the  legal  stage  were  the 
highest  and  last,  as  Moralism  will  have  it  to  be,  then  provision 
would  only  be  made  for  the  distinction  between  God  and 
man,  not  for  their  fellowship  ;  and  this  is  the  position  of  Deism 
and  Pelagianism.  But  God  wills  a  more  intimate  intercourse 
with  man  than  that  brought  about  by  the  stage  of  law  or  of 
right.  On  the  stage  of  right  God  stands  as  Lawgiver  and 
Judge ;  but  in  this  there  is  no  living  fellowship  between  God 
and  man,  they  are  only  related  to  each  other  by  means  of  the 
impersonal  law.  Love  is  possible  only  toward  a  person,  not 
toward  the  abstract  formula  of  the  law.  And  on  the  legal 
stage  the  personality  of  God  is  hidden,  as  it  were,  behind  the 
law.  As  long  as  the  personal  God  reveals  only  what  is 
impersonal,  namely,  His  commands  or  His  will.  He  has  not 
yet  revealed  Himself  fully ;  nay,  the  divine  law  itself  is  not 
yet  fully  revealed,  not  even  when  it  is  love  that  it  demands. 
Eor  it  does  not  as  yet  appear  in  the  form  of  personal  love, 
which  alone  is  its  true  fulfilment,  and  in  which  it  possesses 
attractive    and   inspiring    power.      Thus    it    is   certain    that 


THE  ABSOLUTE  SPHERE.  313 

"  the  law  cannot  make  alive."  When  it  is  said  (Lev.  xviii.  5  ; 
Gal.  iii.  1 2  ;  Heb.  ii.  4),  "  Do  this,  and  thou  shalt  live,"  it 
might  seem  as  if,  after  He  had  given  the  law,  no  further  act 
of  God  was  necessary  for  the  attainment  of  ^coj]  on  the  part  of 
man,  if  only  the  latter  would  do  his  part.  But  the  law,  "  Do 
this,"  etc.,  points  in  its  deepest  aspect  to  religious  duties  also, 
to  humility  and  faith,  to  the  longing  desire  for  fellowship 
with  God  and  for  acts  in  which  God  gives  proof  of  His  love. 
For,  according  to  Paul,  the  law  also  demands  Tr/o-rt?,  that 
humility  which  permits  no  self-sufficiency  or  pride  over 
against  God,  but  which,  impelled  by  gratitude  and  a  sense  of 
need,  depends  wholly  upon  Him  and  His  Spirit  and  seeks 
communion  with  Him.  And  this  shows  that  the  law  points 
for  its  fulfilment  awa}^  beyond  itself.  But  man  cannot  pro- 
duce this  fellowship  of  love  with  God ;  he  has  no  power  over 
God.  In  order  that  real  pleasure  in  and  love  to  God  may  be 
awakened  in  man,  a  higher  act  of  God  is  required  than  the 
giving  of  the  law,  an  act  in  wliicli  God  meets  man  in  love, 
communicates  Himself  to  him,  and  establishes  a  living  and 
loving  relationship  between  them.  Then,  and  only  then,  is 
the  highest  and  permanent  stage  of  morality  possible. 

Now,  since  man  cannot  be  placed  upon  this  stage  at  crea- 
tion, and  cannot  reach  it  by  the  law  or  by  any  efforts  of  his 
own,  since,  on  the  contrary,  it  presupposes  a  revelation  on  the 
part  of  God,  and  one,  too,  that  is  not  merely  ideal  or  addressed 
to  the  intelligence,  but  real,  forming  a  fellowship  between 
God  and  man, — since  this  is  the  case,  the  following  conse- 
quences ensue.  Man  can  only  reach  the  highest  moral  stage 
through  the  consummation  of  the  revelation  of  God ;  and  the 
highest  and  best  that  he  can  effect  in  a  moral  direction,  before 
this  revelation  has  been  made,  simply  cultivates  his  spiritual 
receptivity  and  his  longing  after  the  self-revealing  God. 

§  34ffi.   (Contimcation.) 

The  LnjKrfcction  of  the  Stage  of  Laiu  in  the  Secondary  Spheres 

of  Bight. 

With  regard  to  the  secondary  spheres  also  the  stage  of  law 
exhibits  many  imperfections ;  and  these  are  not  got  rid  of, 
inasmuch  as  moral  energy  cannot  reach  its  full  strength  on 


314  §  34a.    IMPERFECTION  OF  THE  STAGE  OF  LAW  IN 

this  stage,  nor  can  the  law  preserve  these  spheres  from  the 
ruinous  effects  of  self-will.  This  can  only  be  done  by  love, 
which  restrains  self-will  in  the  right  way  (§  31.  3,  4).  The 
law  no  doubt  brings  marriage  and  the  family  under  the  point 
of  view  of  duty  (§  33a.  2).  But  no  arguments  are  required 
to  sliow  that  mere  duty,  although  it  is  higher  than  natural 
love,  is  not  the  perfect  bond  in  these  relations.  Nature  has 
already  infused  into  them  a  warmth  and  intimacy  which, 
while  liable  to  change  aiid  not  proceeding  from  inward  moral 
motives,  yet  could  not  be  replaced  by  the  mere  consciousness 
of  duty.  Besides,  even  should  natural  love  continue  to  exist 
along  with  this  sense  of  duty,  it  could  not  be  compared  with 
the  closeness  and  firmness  of  the  bond  that  is  formed  where 
husband,  wife,  and  the  members  of  the  family  all  recognise  that 
they  are  gifts  of  God  to  each  other,  and  thus  in  Him  become 
objects  to  each  other  of  mutual  respect,  love,  and  joy.  A 
similar  truth  holds  good  with  regard  to  social  intercourse. 
Social  enjoyment  and  friendship,  when  they  reach  their  purest 
and  highest  point,  cannot  but  involuntarily  point  friends 
upward.  The  love  of  friends,  in  its  deepest  form,  has  a 
natural  tendency  to  seek  a  foundation  in  love  to  God. 

Even  with  respect  to  the  State  itself,  which  is  the  product 
of  the  legal  stage,  it  must  be  said  that  it  cannot  here  reach 
its  perfect  form.  If  there  were  no  higher  form  of  society 
than  the  State,  then  it  would  have  to  be  accepted  as  the  last 
and  absolutely  the  highest  of  human  communities,  as  the 
representative  of  human  morality  in  the  whole  of  its  compass. 
Now,  although  it  might  not  of  necessity  follow  that  finite 
interests  would  thereby  be  deified, — for  in  that  case  sin 
would  be  admitted, — although,  on  the  contrary,  men  were  to 
remain  mindful  of  the  connection  between  human  rights 
and  the  divine  law,  still  the  only  result  would  be  a  legal 
theocracy,  in  which  the  religious  and  the  political  would  be 
side  by  side  with  relatively  no  distinction  between  them. 
But  this  state  of  things  could  only  be  acquiesced  in  from  a 
religious  point  of  view,  if  religion  were  still  at  the  stage  of 
law;  and  this,  as  we  have  just  seen  (§  34),  is  an  intermediate, 
not  a  final  stage  in  its  progress.  When  religion,  that  is,  is  still 
in  its  legal  form,  it  is  quite  in  keeping  therewith  that  the 
chief  stress   should  be  laid  upon  visible,  external  actions,  a 


THE  SECONDAKY  SPHERES.       THE  STATE.  315 

good  intention  perhaps  being  presupposed.  But,  on  tlie 
contrary,  the  more  that  advancing  moral  knowledge  penetrates 
within,  and  learns  to  attach  an  independent  importance  to 
the  inward  disposition  out  of  which  acts  arise,  the  more  does 
the  human  spirit  outgrow  the  political  form  of  religion,  in 
which  religion  is  bound  up  with  a  particular  form  of  national 
life. 

Further,  the  State  itself  would  not  be  absolutely  secure 
in  its  right,  unless  morality  were  to  reach  its  highest 
development  in  the  consummation  of  revelation  and  religion. 
The  individual  and  the  community  are  not  of  absolute 
value  until  they  are  actually  moral.  Before  this  time 
arrives,  their  absolute  worth  exists  only  in  hope,  or  hypo- 
thetically.  Now  the  State  derives  its  divine  right  from 
the  fact  that  it  protects  this  their  ideal  moral  perfection, 
or  makes  possible  their  free  development  towards  it. 
Hence,  should  the  legal  stage  never  be  surpassed,  sliould 
therefore  the  principle  of  true  morality  never  be  realized, 
the  State  would  for  ever  lack  the  very  thing  which  makes 
it  itself  a  good  of  absolute  value.  In  fact,  right  derives 
its  majesty  in  the  last  resort  from  love,  of  which  it  is  the 
negative  manifestation.  Moreover,  there  must  be  progress 
on  the  part  of  the  State ;  hence  the  State  must  exhibit  pro- 
ductive energy,  even  with  regard  to  legislation.  And  such 
energy  cannot  be  derived  from  intelligence  alone ;  like  all 
faithful  discharge  of  duty,  it  springs  from  love. 

In  the  third  place,  the  State  cannot  be  the  moral  community 
that  embraces  men  in  general.  It  is  too  weak  and  narrow  a 
bond  for  this  purpose.  If  the  principle  of  individuality  is  to 
receive  justice,  the  State  must  of  necessity  exist  as  one  among 
a  plurality  of  States ;  it  must  have  its  own  distinct  national 
and  terrestrial  basis,  its  connection  with  a  certain  land  and  a 
certain  people.  Thus  each  is  a  particular  State,  and  the 
existence  of  a  universal  State  is  utterly  impossible.  Each 
one  in  maintaining  its  rights  may  come  into  collision  with 
other  States,  and  this  collision  can  be  brought  to  a  definite 
close  by  force  alone.  In  its  own  domain  it  is  the  highest 
and  sovereign  source  of  right ;  it  must  refuse  to  acknowledge 
any  earthly  judge  over  it  to  settle  the  collisions  that  occur. 
Finally,  the  State  requires  the  positive  principle  of  love,  and 


316  §  35.    THE  STAGE  OF  LAW  IN  KEFERENCE  TO  SIN. 

not  only  of  right,  to  form  a  bond  of  union  between  its 
citizens ;  for  the  crises  which  it  must  encounter  it  requires 
patriotism,  that  pure  productive  sense  for  all  progress  in  law 
and  government  (cf.  §  75). 

Thus  the  State,  that  is,  the  community  founded  upon  right, 
points  on  all  sides  to  a  higher  community,  which  reaches  out 
beyond  the  differences  that  separate  nations,  and  releases  them 
even  from  the  refined  egoism  of  patriotism — a  community 
which  has  the  power  to  control  these  differences,  to  knit  the 
nations  together  as  members  of  historical  humanity,  and  to 
make  them  as  it  were  brothers  and  sisters  in  one  universal 
family,  founded  upon  the  positive  principle  of  love.  And 
this  is  the  Church,  the  community  to  which  religion  when 
perfected  gives  rise,  in  which  the  unity  of  humanity  is  for  the 
first  time  realized  in  a  moral  form — nay,  in  which  it  becomes 
an  ethical  product  and  an  ethical  good.  Man  lives  not  by 
I'ight  alone,  but  by  every  word  that  proceedeth  out  of  the 
mouth  of  God,  and  above  all,  by  that  Word  which  is  the 
consummation  both  of  revelation  and  religion,  the  Word 
that  was  made  flesh. 


CHAPTER    SECOND. 

the  stage  of  law  with  reference  to  sin  (ethical 
ponerology). 

§  35,  Cf  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  vol  ii.  §  72-78, 
vol,  iii,  §  78-84,  §  89, 

The  possibility  of  moral  evil  is  given  in  the  original  constitu- 
tion of  man's  moral  nature.  When  it  becomes  actual, 
the  insufficiency  of  the  law,  without  a  new  and  in  the 
first  place  an  atoning  and  redeeming  manifestation  on 
the  part  of  God,  becomes  still  more  evident. 

[Literature, — Christ.  Fr.  Schmid,  Dc  Peccato,  Partic.  i.-iii. 
Bihlischc  Thcolof/ie  n.  T.,  3rd  ed,  1864.  Christl.  Sittcnlehre,  1861. 
Ernesti,  Vmn  Urspomng  der  SiXndc  nach  pcmlinischen  Lehrgehcdt, 
2  vols.  1855, 1862.  Baur,  Tlicologic  dcs  ncucn  Testaments,  1864. 
JPaidus,  1845,      Holsten,  Die   Bedeutung  dcs   Wortes    cdp^  im 


LITERATURE.  317 

ncucn  Testament,  1853.  Bas  Evangclium  des  Faulus  und 
Pdrus,  1868.  Liidemann,  Antliro'pologi&  des  Apostels  Faulus, 
1872,  Wendt,  Die  Begriffe  Flcisch  und  Geist  im  hihlischcn 
Sprachgebrauch,  1878.  Pfleiderer,  Faidinismus,  1873.  Weiss, 
Lckrhuch  der  liUischen  Thcologie,  3rd  ed.  1880,  §  21,  46,  56, 
66,  70,  100,  115,  148,  151,  157.  Vilmar,  Was  fasst  der 
Ijiblische  Begriff  der  Silnde  in  sich  und  giebt  es  nach  diesem  eine 
Erlsiinde?  1840.  M.enegoz,  Ze  peche  et  la  redemption  d'apres 
St.  Faul,  1882.  Delitzsch,  System  der  hihlischen  Psychologie. 
Beck,  Umriss  der  hihlischen  Seclenlchre,  1871.  Kern,  Uehcr  die 
Silnde.  Tuhinger  Zeitschrift,  1832, 1,  3.  Slirm,  Anthropologisclie 
Untersuehungcn.  Tuhinger  Zeitschrift,  1834,  3.  Krabbe,  Bie 
Zchre  von  der  Silnde  und  vom  Tode,  1836.  J.  Muller,  The 
Christian  Doctrine  of  Sin,  vol.  ii.  (criticized  by  Vatke,  Hallische 
Jahrhilchcr,  1840,  and  by  the  author  in  Eeuter's  Bepcrtorium^ 
1845).  Von  Hofmann,  Schrifthciveis,  1857,  i.  444,  505.  Theolo- 
qisclie  Ethik,  1878,  p.  32  sq.  Marteusen,  Christian  Ethics,  i.  p. 
98  sq.  (360  sq.),  ii.  p.  84  sq.  Eothe,  Thcol.  Ethik,  1st  ed.  vol. 
i.  §  28,  31,  44,  98,  121-123 ;  vol.  ii.  pp.  170-251  (2nd  ed. 
§  40,  55,  83).  Sartorius,  The  Boctrine  of  Bivine  Love. 
Tholuck,  Von  der  Silnde  und  dem  Versohner,  8th  ed.  1862, 
Liebner,  Kicler  allg.  Monatserift  f.  Wiss.  und  Lit.  1851,  p. 
163  sq.  Vilmar,  7l/o?rf/.  V\\\\v^]i\,  Kirchl.  Glaiihenslehrc,  \ol.  iii. 
Thomasius,  Christi  Ferson  und  Wcrk,  vol.  i.  2nd  ed.  1856. 
Bogmatik,  vol.  i,  Schweizer,  Bie  christliche  Glaubenslehre 
nach  irrotestantischcn  Grundsdtzen,  1863,  i.  329.  Weisse,  Fhilos. 
Bogmcdik,  ii.  p.  391  sq.  Biedermann,  Christi.  Bogmatik,  1869, 
pp.  411  sq.,  594  sq.,  669  sq.  Pfleiderer,  Grundriss  der  christi. 
Glauhcns  und  Sittenlehre,  pp.  112  sq.,  257  sq.  Heinrici,  Bie 
Silnde  nach  Wesen  und  JJrsprung,  1878.  Kaehler,  Bas  Gewissen, 
i.  1, 1878,  pp.  216  sq.,  294  sq.  Bie  Wissenschaft  der  christlichen- 
Lehre,  Nr.  2,  p.  289  sq.  Frank,  System  der  christlichen  Wahr- 
heit,  1878,  i.  p.  400.  Si/stem  der  christi.  Sittlichkeit,  1884,  i.  p. 
104  sq.  Ritschl,  Rcchtfertigung  und  Versohnung,  2nd  ed.  vol. 
iii.  chap.  v.     Kreibig,  Versohnung slehre,  1878,  pp.  21-46. 

Philosophy  :  Spinoza,  Ethik.  Leibnitz,  Theodicee.  King,  Be- 
origine  mali.  Kant,  Religion  innerhcdh  der  Gri^enzen  hlosser 
Vernunft.  Kritik  der  praktischen  Vernunft.  Pichte,  Sitten- 
lehre, 1798,  1812.  Schelling,  Fhilosophie  und  Beligion.  Frei- 
hcitslchrc.  Fhilosophie  der  Offenharung,  2  vols.  Bockshanmier, 
Bie  Frciheit  des  mcnschlichen  Willens,  1821.  Daub,  Judas 
Lscharioth.  Herbart,  Gesprdeh  ilher  das  Lose,  1817.  Schleier- 
macher,  Abhandlung  ilher  die  Erivdhlungslehre.  Gkmhcnslehre, 
i.  §  65-74,  79-81.  Entiourf  eines  Systems  der  Sittenlehre,  ed. 
Schweizer,  pp.  52  sq.,  71,  421  sq.  Ptitter,  Ueher  das  Bose, 
1869.     Steffens,  Christi.  Religionsphilosophie,  ii.  1-100.     Hegel, 


318  §  35.    THE  STAGE  OF  LAW  IN  EEFERENCE  TO  SIN. 

Fhatiomcnolofjic  and  BecMspMlosophie.  Vatke,  Die  menscJdiche 
Freilicit  im  Vcrhditniss  zur  Sunde  mid  gottlichen  Gnade,  1841. 
Marheiuecke,  Dorjmatilc,  1847,  p.  196  sq.  Wirth,  System  der 
^pclcidafivm  Ethil;  vol.  i.  1841,  pp.  41-50,  Il7-15i5.  I.  H. 
Fichte,  Anthropolorjie,  1857.  System  dei'  MhiJc.  Benecke, 
Grundlinien  d.  naturlichen  Si/stems  der  praJctischen  Philosophie. 
Kym,  Das  Froblem  des  Bosen,  1878.  Hartmann,  Phdnomenologie 
des  situ.  Bewusstseins.  Scholteii,  Der  freie  Wille,  pp.  127- 
166.— Ed.] 

1.  Sin  is  not  a  mere  defect,  involved  in  finiteness,  which 
is  a  natural  necessity,  nor  does  it  consist  in  the  mere  fact  that 
the  good  which  ought  to  be  does  not  yet  exist ;  but  it  is  a 
false  position,  love  of  the  creature  in  opposition  to  God,  and 
is  therefore  avo/xia  (1  John  iii.  4).  To  stand  on  the 
wrong  line  is  a  different  thing  from  standing  at  the  com- 
mencement of  the  right  one ;  the  former  means  digression,  the 
latter  progression.  Palse  creature-love  may  incline  to  the 
form  of  love  of  the  world,  i.e.  concealed  selfishness,  or  to  that 
of  more  direct  selfishness,  but  it  always  involves  opposition 
to  God,  our  sense  of  God  has  become  obscured  and  feeble. 
Moral  evil  does  not  become  actual  without  a  sufficient  cause. 
That  cause  is  freedom  in  tlie  sense  of  self-will,  which,  though 
it  does  not  act  without  a  motive,  still  acts  without  one  that  is 
morally  sufticient.  In  self-will,  one  factor  in  the  whole  notion 
of  freedom  isolates  itself  and  seeks  to  become  the  whole  of 
freedom.  It  breaks  away  from  the  law,  which,  as  we  have 
seen,  is  an  original  and  essential  element  in  freedom  (not, 
however,  in  the  shape  of  a  mere  compulsory  power).  Hence 
there  exists  a  general  similarity  among  all  the  manifold 
appearances  taken  by  moral  evil,  a  similarity  arising  from  the 
fact  that  in  every  case  evil  is  a  contradiction  both  of  the  law 
of  God  and  of  the  essential  nature  of  man,  and  produces  dis- 
cord within  him.  And  this  it  does  all  the  more,  because, 
according  to  the  constitution  of  human  nature,  every  Actus 
goes  to  produce  a  habit  of  action,  a  fact  wdiich  throws  light 
upon  the  connection  of  evil  in  the  race.  For  the  race  is  a 
unity  of  solidarity ;  moral  evil,  therefore,  seizes,  though  by 
degrees,  upon  the  whole  organism  of  humanity,  ruins  the 
virtuous  energy  of  man,  his  spiritual  endowments,  his  moral 
aims,  and  in  consequence  even  his  moral  knowledge  as  well. 

2.  ]\Ioreover,  sin  makes  clear  from    a   new   side   the    in- 


NECESSITY  OF  A  HIGHER  REVELATION.  319 

sufficiency  or  rather  the  powerlessness  of  the  legal  standpoint. 
The  law  indeed  does  not  give  way,  it  offers  resistance ;  but 
this  only  excites  the  false  freedom  still  more.  Further,  it 
threatens  and  punishes  and  puts  a  check  upon  outbreaks ; 
but  the  only  result  is  that  one  form  of  egoism  is  exchanged 
for  another.  It  gives  notice  of  punishment,  it  pronounces  the 
sinner  guilty  and  lays  a  ban  upon  him ;  but  the  ban  does  not 
make  him  moral  in  a  living  sense,  it  only  robs  him  of  vital 
energy  and  cows  him.  It  might  perhaps  prompt  him  to  retire 
within  himself,  to  acknowledge  that  he  deserves  punishment, 
and  to  be  ready  to  bear  the  displeasure  of  God  which  he  has 
incurred;  but  actually  to  bear  that  displeasure  would  presuppose 
a  love  of  justice,  a  power  of  truthfulness, — in  a  single  word,  a 
degree  of  morality  which  is  just  the  very  thing  that  the  sinner 
lacks,  as  long  as  he  remains  thrown  back  upon  himself.  And 
he  lacks  it  all  the  more  for  this  reason,  that  actual  sin  passes 
over  into  habitual,  and  thus  a  nexus  of  evil  is  formed  both  in 
the  individual  and  throughout  the  race,  an  evil  tendency  that 
continually  increases  in  power.  Man  cannot  atone  for  him- 
self ;  and  yet,  since  the  grace  of  God  like  His  displeasure  is 
always  just,  atonement  is  the  first  thing  which  he  needs,  in 
order  that  he  may  again  enter  into  that  loving  communion 
with  God  which  is  the  source  of  all  true  morality. 

3.  Although  punishment  is  necessary,  and  even  a  blessing, 
in  the  order  of  the  world,  yet  the  punitive  justice  of  God 
does  not  require  that  it  itself  should  be  His  final  revelation. 
It  is  not  necessary  that  God  should  leave  moral  evil  to  take 
its  own  course,  which  inevitably  leads  to  dircoXeia.  As  is 
shown  more  explicitly  in  Dogmatics,-^  God  remains  free, 
even  when  sin  has  arisen,  to  make  an  atoning  and  redeeming 
revelation,  as  long  as  the  evil-doer  has  not  become  absolutely 
hardened  and  unimpressible.  And  this  he  cannot  be  before 
the  atoning  revelation  is  made ;  for  only  in  it  has  the  clearest 
revelation  of  divine  love  been  given.  Hence  it  follows  that 
he  who  has  not  yet  rejected  it  has  not  yet  set  himself  in 
absolute  opposition  to  the  Good  in  its  fullest  manifestation, 
has  not  yet  united  and  identified  himself  with  the  principle 
of  evil, — and  therefore,  that  forgiveness  is  still  possible  for 
him  (Eom.  iii.  25,  26  ;  Luke  xxiii.  34  ;  Eev.  xvii.  30). 
^  Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  ii.  §  61,  iii.  §  89. 


320  §  3ia.    ACTUAL  EXISTENCE  OF  SIN  IN  HUMANITY. 

In  accordance  with  our  Syllabus  (§  32),  we  have  now  con- 
sidered in  the  First  Section  of  our  Third  Division  the  advance 
which  is  made  in  the  ethical  process  by  the  stage  of  law  or  of 
right;  in  the  Second  Section  (§  34,  35),  the  imperfection  of 
the  legal  stage,  both  apart  from  sin  and  with  special  reference 
to  sin;  in  the  Third  Section  we  have  still  to  take  up  the  stage 
of  love  or  of  the  gospel,  as  the  contents  of  the  ethical  world- 
ideal,  in  which  the  ethical  process  reaches  its  consummation. 
Vicl  §  32,  p.  300. 

[JSfofe. — At  this  point  tlie  author  had,  at  an  earlier  period, 
added  two  more  paragraphs,  treating  of  sin  as  it  actually  exists 
in  the  history  of  mankind,  and  of  that  historical  counteraction 
of  good  against  evil  which  formed  the  positive  preparation  for 
the  principle  of  Christianity.  I  give  these  paragraphs  in  §  35a, 
35&.— Ed.] 

§  35a.   The  Actual  Existence  of  Sin  in  Humanity. 

The  three  stages  which  have  been  derived  from  the  essential 
nature  of  morality  (§  5.  3  ;  9« ;  18  ;  19  ;  32.  2,  3)  are 
also  exemplified  in  history,  which  consequently  affords 
proof  that  the  divine  World-Ideal  is  actually  realized  in 
the  way  which  we  find  to  be  logically  necessary  when 
we  consider  the  nature  of  that  ideal  itself  Moreover, 
both  Scripture  and  experience  give  their  testimony  that 
sin — which  is  logically  no  more  than  j^ossihle — has 
become  a  universal  fact,  assuming  the  two  forms  of 
pagan  and  Jewish  sin,  of  carnal  selfishness  and  spiritual 
selfishness  or  pride,  eudaimonistic  Antinomianism  and 
ITomism.  Experience  likewise  confirms  the  truth  that 
an  abnormal  process  goes  on  in  which  acts  that  contra- 
dict duty  pass  into  and  become  vice  or  evil  habit,  which, 
on  its  side  again,  reacts  upon  human  freedom,  enslaving 
and  limiting  it.  The  result  of  this  action  and  reaction 
is  that  the  moral  nature  of  man  becomes  more  and  more 
corrupted,  and  he  approaches  that  which  is  the  opposite 
of  the  Supreme  Good — viz.  Supreme  Evil.  And  although 
this    corruption    does   not    exclude     the    possibility    of 


HEATHEN  AND  JEWISH  SIN".  321 

redemption  and  final  perfection,  still  the  resistance  made 
to  evil  in  pre-Christian  times — and  which  has  never 
been  wholly  wanting — by  conscience  and  the  law,  by 
political  enactments,  sages,  and  rulers,  was  unable  to 
check  it.  In  fact,  the  power  of  sin  makes  it  all  the 
more  necessary,  from,  a  new  side,  that  an  act  of  God 
should  take  place,  of  an  atoning  kind,  in  which  revela- 
tion is  carried  past  the  stage  of  law. 

1.  With  reference  to  the  universality  of  moral  evil  we  shall 
only  mention  the  following  passages  of  Scripture :  Kom.  i.-iii., 
V.  12f.;  Gen.  iii.,  of.  vi.  Iff.;  Eph.  ii.  3  ;  1  Cor.  xv.  22; 
John  iii.  5  f. ;  Jas.  iii.  2  (C.  A.  II.).  Although  all  evil 
involves  a  turning  away  from  God,  yet  it  takes  a  double  form, 
and  has  a  double  course. 

(a)  The  godless  tendency  of  the  person  may  take  the  form 
of  weakness  as  against  the  influence  of  the  world  of  the  mani- 
fold, with  which  we  are  brought  into  connection  by  the  senses. 
In  this  case  the  natural  will  or  the  lower  impulses  are 
stimulated  and  become  predominant,  while  the  rational  nature 
becomes  feeble  and  passive.  And  this  is  sensuality.  In  it, 
however,  there  is  also  spontaneity  on  the  part  of  the  person, 
i'or  after  the  temptation  has  seduced  and  mastered  the  will, 
it  makes  the  will  and  consequently  the  whole  man  its  organ 
for  carrying  out  the  sin  which  promises  to  give  pleasure,  and 
thus  he  becomes  the  servant  of  the  sensual  side  of  his  nature. 
Here  we  have  sin  in  its  specifically  heathen  shape,  that  of 
EudiBmonism,  in  which  the  will  submits  to  the  sway  of  carnal 
desire  or  the  sensual  side  of  human  nature,  and  resolves  to 
strive  after  its  gratification. 

(h)  The  other,  more  spiritual  form  of  the  godless  tendency 
shows  perhaps  more  energy  and  independence  as  against  the 
influence  of  the  world,  owing  to  the  increased  strength  which 
self-consciousness  receives  from  the  law ;  but  it  may  for  all 
that  take  a  form  still  more  impious  and  alienated  from  God, 
as  when  the  spirit  shuts  itself  up  in  self-satisfaction  and  denies 
its  creaturely  dependence,  or,  should  these  characteristics  be 
hypocritically  concealed,  when  it  exhibits  spiritual  or  moral 
pride  and  legal  righteousness.     This  form  of  sin  has  appeared 

X 


322  §  35a.    ACTUAL  EXISTENCE  OF  SIN  IN  HUMANITY. 

under  the  Jewish  law  (in  Pharisaism),  and  is  all  the  more 
dangerous  because  it  is  more  or  less  veiled,  and  preserves  the 
appearance  of  obedience  toward  God.  It  is  sin  in  its  speci- 
fically Jewish  shape,  the  abnormal  as  it  appears  on  the  stage 
of  law.  There  are  general  principles,  ever  returning  types  of 
evil,  which  have  made  their  historical  appearance  in  large  and 
compact  forms,  in  heathenism  and  Judaism.  Let  us  look  a 
little  more  closely  at  these  two  great  divisions  of  the  ancient 
world,  and  trace  the  development  of  evil  in  them. 

2.  With  regard  to  heathenism,  as  it  appears  in  history,  no 
profounder  derivation  of  it  could  be  given  than  in  the  words 
of  Paul  (Eom.  i.),  "  They  did  not  give  thanks  to  God, 
and  thus  they  became  vain  in  their  reasonings."  They  did 
not  gratefully  refer  their  enjoyments  and  blessings  to  God, 
thus  consecrating  them  and  overcoming  their  /xaTat6rr]<i  ;  they 
never  got  beyond  these  gifts  themselves,  and  thus  their  sense 
of  the  world  became  overpoweringly  strong,  while  their  sense 
of  God  and  their  self-consciousness  as  spiritual  beings  became 
weak.  Heathenism  acknowledges  the  supremacy  of  nature 
over  the  spirit  by  deifying  the  former  and  secularizing  tlie 
latter ;  it  has  as  many  gods  as  it  has  goods.  Along  with  the 
unity  and  absoluteness  of  the  idea  of  God,  which  this  worldly 
bias  breaks  up  into  a  multiplicity  of  gods,  the  absoluteness  of 
the  moral  law  also  disappears.  The  gods  themselves  commit 
sin.  Caprice  and  Fate  at  least  take  precedence  of  the  moral 
law.  IMoreover,  just  as  selfishness,  which  is  the  opposite  of 
love,  lies  hid  in  the  carnal  spirit,  so  the  natural  religions  con- 
tain what  is  the  very  opposite  of  true  religion.  Por  their 
gods  are  not  worshipped  from  love  to  anything  in  them 
that  is  worthy  of  love ;  on  the  contrary,  they  both  exist 
and  are  worshipped  for  the  purpose  of  being  serviceable 
and  favourable  to  human  aims.  Accordingly,  they  are  essen- 
tially guardian  gods  of  a  country,  a  city,  or  a  family. 
And  since  they  are  thus  worshipped  chiefly  on  account  of 
finite  interests, — a  fact  which  is  most  apparent  in  the  religion 
of  Eome, — a  false  bent  of  the  heart  here  makes  itself 
apparent. 

Connected  with  this  thorough  egoism  also,  there  is  the 
exclusive  spirit  manifested  by  ancient  nations.  This  is  seen 
in    the    opposition   between   Hellenes   or  even   Eomans    and 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  EVIL  IN  THE  HEATHEN'  WOELD.  323 

barbarians,  in  the  East  between  sacred  lands  and  profane ;  as 
well  as  in  the  distinction  of  castes,  the  treatment  of  a  part  of 
mankind  as  slaves  (a  practice  which  Aristotle  could  defend, 
without  contradiction  from  the  public  conscience),  and  finally, 
in  the  degradation  of  women — especially  in  the  East  and 
in  Hellas — and  the  tyrannical  rights  exercised  by  parents 
over  children,  especially  in  Kome.  The  old  heathen  world 
had  no  idea  of  the  infinite  worth  of  the  individual  human 
being — a  truth  which  is  of  such  vast  influence  upon  marriage 
and  the  family.  Nay,  Art  even,  however  much  it  flourished 
in  Greece,  was  too  deficient  in  a  sense  of  the  infinite  signi- 
ficance of  life.  Hence  it  was  that  its  palmy  days  were  so  few, 
and  its  constructive  power  was  so  soon  exhausted.  With  the 
downfall  of  religious  faith — to  which  the  Mysteries  only  gave 
artificial  life  for  a  little — art  lost  its  strength  and  purity, 
through  the  supremacy  of  the  natural  over  the  spiritual ;  it 
grew  more  and  more  rank,  but  more  and  more  empty  and  life- 
less. At  the  same  time  Science  degenerated  into  scepticism, 
and  to  this  scepticism  the  followers  of  Aristotle  and  of  Plato 
alike  succumbed. 

With  respect,  finally,  to  the  State,  the  highest  moral  com- 
munity which  the  heathen  world  knew,  Plato's  Republic  is 
enough  to  show  how  the  other  moral  spheres  of  life  must 
suffer,  when  the  State  is  made  the  absolute  moral  community, 
and  everything  else — e.g.  the  individual,  marriage,  family — is 
regarded  merely  as  a  means  for  its  ends.  As  we  have  seen, 
the  duty  of  the  State  is  to  afford,  in  the  name  of  justice,  its 
protecting  power  to  every  good  that  exists,  and  so  to  guarantee 
to  it  the  possibility  of  development.  But  since  antiquity 
knows  no  absolute  World-goal,  so  for  the  most  part  right  itself 
is  not  conceived  of  as  having  absolute  ends  to  serve,  and  thus 
it  lacks  objective  stability.  The  good  things  which  are  distinct 
from  the  State,  but  which  the  latter  has  to  protect,  are  not 
recognised  in  their  absolute  value  ;  thus  the  State  remains  as 
the  absolute  end,  and  tliis  involves  an  apotheosis  of  power  and 
finite  interests,  or  of  a  particular  nation.  The  greatest 
attempt  made  by  the  ancient  world  in  the  way  of  a  State — 
Eome,  namely — has  no  respect  for  foreign  nationalities  ;  in  its 
gigantic  egoism  it  seeks  only  to  absorb  them  all  in  itself.  No 
doubt  a  kind  of   universality  seems  to  be  attained   in  this 


324  §  35a.     ACTUAL  EXISTENCE  OF  SIN  IN  HUMANITY. 

State;  national  limitations  are  broken  down  {jus  gentium,  jus 
naturalc),  nations  are  gathered  into  one  kingdom,  and  the  idea 
of  the  unity  of  humanity  can  now  assert  itself  with  greater 
freedom.  Nevertheless,  we  have  here  only  the  shadow  of 
true  universality ;  it  is  preponderantly  negative  and  empty. 
All  that  has  happened  is  that  the  particular  national- 
ism of  Kome  has  attained  universal  power ;  it  has  come 
as  a  judgment  upon  the  eudcemonistic  world  of  sense,  but 
it  has  brought  nothing  better  in  the  place  of  the  latter. 
And  these  very  instruments  of  the  judgment  of  God,  the 
Eomans,  these  murderers  of  the  liberties  of  nations,  are  them- 
selves overtaken  by  a  righteous  fate.  This  nation,  whose 
liighest  good  is  power,  fame,  and  dominion,  and  which  has 
made  these  its  aims,  has  to  fall  at  last  under  the  despotism  of 
the  Csesars.  After  the  Eomans  have  crushed  the  liberty  and 
prosperity  of  all  nations,  it  becomes  clear  that  all  the  while 
they  have  been  digging  a  grave  for  their  own  prosperity  and 
freedom.  They  now  drag  out  an  empty,  material  existence, 
filled  with  life's  weariness;  unless  disgust  with  public  and 
national  affairs  impels  them  to  seek  that  inward  comfort  and 
consolation  which  just  at  this  time  Christianity  comes  forward 
to  offer. 

3.  The  Hebrews  too,  even  witli  the  help  of  the  Old  Testa- 
ment, were  not  in  reality  more  successful.  We  might  point  to 
the  facts  that  polygamy  was  not  forbidden,  and  that  an  almost 
unlimited  wantonness  prevailed  in  the  practice  of  divorce 
(]\Iatt.  V.) ;  that  art  and  science  were  but  sparingly  developed ; 
that  the  union  of  the  political  and  the  religious  community  in 
a  theocracy  was  a  hindrance  both  to  the  State  and  to  religion, 
preventing  each  of  them  from  shaping  itself  according  to  its 
own  principle ;  and  that  when  the  two  became  separated  in 
consequence  of  the  intervention  of  heathen  power,  the  separa- 
tion was  submitted  to  unwillingly,  and  gave  rise  to  impotent 
attempts  to  set  up  a  theocracy  again.  But  apart  from  all 
this,  what  we  would  chiefly  call  attention  to  is  the  intense 
and  sinful  national  pride  which  the  Hebrews  displayed  toward 
other  peoples, — as  seen,  e.g.,  in  the  Book  of  Esther  and  the 
Eeast  of  Purim, — a  pride  which  drove  them  to  that  national 
hatred  of  the  heathen  which  the  latter  on  their  part  returned 
but    too    cordially,    designating    the    Jews     "  odium    generis 


JEWISH  FORMS  OF  SIN.  32o 

hnmani."  In  addition  to  this  there  was  also  their  pride  in 
the  knovjlcdge  of  the  law  (Eom.  ii.  18  ff.).  But  as  far  as  the 
fulfilment  of  the  law  is  concerned,  down  to  the  exile  the  mass 
of  the  people  was  constantly  inclined  to  fall  away  into 
heathenism,  a  tendency  which  continued  at  a  later  date  in  a 
more  refined  but  not  a  better  form,  viz.  in  Sadduceism. 

After  the  exile,  moreover,  when  the  law  as  an  external 
principle  was  fully  carried  out,  a  spirit  of  mechanical  legalism 
and  adherence  to  the  letter  became  prevalent,  in  which  the 
chief  place  was  given  to  outward  works,  while  the  inward  side 
of  the  law,  the  circumcision  of  the  heart,  the  spiritual  sacrifice 
of  repentance  and  thanksgiving,  was  thrust  into  the  back- 
ground (Deut.  X.  16,  XXX.  6  ;  Lev.  xix.  17,  18  ;  Isa.  i.  11-18; 
Ps.  1.  16,  li.  12  ;  Hos.  vi.  6  ;  Prov.  xv.  8,  26,  xxi.  3  ;  Amos 
V.  24).  An  exuberant,  casuistical  ingenuity  was  shown  in 
setting  fence  after  fence  around  the  law  ;  men  tried  to  advance 
in  righteousness  by  increasing  the  number  of  legal  precepts, 
instead  of  by  giving  heed  to  the  relation  of  the  heart  to  the 
law  ;  they  never  thought  of  asking  whether  the  inward  motive 
was  a  merely  mercenary  one,  or  the  fear  of  punishment,  or 
whether  it  was  love  to  God.  And  at  the  same  time  this  legal 
and  not  very  difficult  fulfilment  of  the  law  was  combined  with 
moral  pride,  a  self-righteousness  which  disowned  both  humility 
toward  God  and  love  toward  one's  fellow-men.  No  doubt 
upright  souls  were  not  wanting,  who  preserved  themselves 
alike  from  Pharisaism  and  Sadduceism  ;  but  these  were  the 
very  persons  who  looked  for  a  true  atonement  in  place  of 
animal  sacrifices,  and  awaited  a  new  revelation,  recognisincf 
that  even  the  Hebrew  people  had  outlived  its  day,  if  the 
regeneration  did  not  come  which  the  prophets  had  promised. 

§  35&.  The  Historical  Counteraction  of  Good  against  Evil,  and 
the  Positive  Freyarcdion  for  the  Fvinci'plc  of  Christian 
Morality. 

However  great  the  power  of  evil  became  before  the  time  of 
Christ,  and  however  great  it  still  continues  to  be,  yet 
man's  need  of  redemption  has  never  gone  so  far  as  to 
make  him  inccvpcible  of  redemption.  The  stages  in  the 
ethical   process    which    we    have  seen   to   be   logically 


326  §  356.     COUNTEEACTION  OF  GOOD  AGAINST  EVIL. 

necessary  are  not  obliterated  by  the  power  of  evil.  On 
the  contrary,  they  continue  to  unfold  themselves,  and 
are  promoted  by  the  good  influences  which  are  at  work 
in  opposition  to  evil,  due  to  the  constitution  of  man's 
moral  nature  and  to  the  progress  of  historical  revelation. 
While  sin  was  increasing,  the  capacity  of  man  for  re- 
demption was  being  cultivated  into  positive  receptiveness. 
This  took  place  in  two  ways,  (a)  Through  the  unceas- 
ing reaction  of  the  law,  both  ideal  and  real, — a  reaction 
which  is  seen  partly  in  the  political  and  religious  institu- 
tions of  nations  in  general,  and  in  ancient  philosophy, 
partly  and  most  clearly  in  the  Jewish  theocracy  with  its 
objective  law.  (h)  Through  prophecy,  within  the  heathen 
but  more  especially  the  Jewish  world,  which  points  to  a 
new  revelation  and  communication  of  God,  in  which  the 
principle  of  virtue  will  be  truly  realized. 

1.  It  cannot  be  said  that  in  the  pre-Christian  world  sin 
alone  was  developed ;  the  normal  development  of  human 
powers  and  faculties  also  went  on,  as  it  would  have  done  had 
sin  never  entered  at  all.  By  this  means  preparation  is  made 
for  a  perfect  morality ;  and  these  powers,  in  their  highest 
development,  must  be  incorporated  with  the  perfect  ethical 
principle  when  it  has  been  actually  realized.  The  stages,  too, 
which  we  saw  to  be  logically  necessary  appear  in  history  in 
tlie  pre-Christian  world,  and  are  clearly  recognisable.  Eemini- 
scences  of  a  comparatively  pure  and  innocent  golden  age  at 
the  commencement  of  the  race  run  throughout  the  whole  of 
mankind.  That  age  was  followed  by  one  in  which  the  heathen 
world  saw  more  especially  the  predominance  of  evil,  while  the 
Jewish  spirit  saw  in  it  the  fact  of  sin,  which  it  recognises  as 
the  source  of  all  evils.  Nevertheless,  an  advance  has  been 
made  in  the  course  of  this  age ;  the  transition  has  now  been 
effected  to  the  stage  of  law.  Lawgivers  appear,  at  first  as 
heroes  ;  in  the  heathen  and  the  Jewish  world  humanity  is 
upon  the  legal  stage.  Among  the  most  civilised  nations  too, 
a  high  degree  of  culture  was  reached  to  some  extent,  even 
before  Christ  ;  a  contrast  was  set  up  to  the  moral  chaos  that 


CONSCIOUSNESS  OF  GUILT  IN  THE  HEATHEN  WORLD.       327 

existed,  a  certain  natural  refinement  was  attained  through  the 
power  of  culture  and  of  growing  intelligence.  Heathenism 
developed  finely  and  fruitfully  many  parts  of  the  moral 
nature,  especially  in  science,  art,  and  politics.  And  thougli 
there  is  still  wanting  the  pure  ethical  spirit,  to  make  all 
these  achievements  its  earthly  body  as  it  were  and  give  them 
life,  and  though  they  thus  remain  inlierently  perishable,  they 
yet  form  a  preparation  for  morality  in  its  perfect  shape.  For 
the  latter  requires  an  external  form  in  which  to  realize  itself ; 
and  in  this  direction  the  ancient  world  did  much  good  service 
in  its  own  way. 

2.  Further,  swi  was  opposed  by  the  consciousness  of  guilt 
and  of  punishment.  "Arrj  with  her  expiations  plays  a  large 
part  in  Greek  Tragedy,  in  Aeschylus  and  Sophocles,  in  the 
Prometheus  myth,  in  the  Antigone  and  Oedipus.  The 
Delphic  temple  in  particular  had  expiatory  rites.  Apollo  was 
regarded  as  the  purifying  and  atoning  god,  who  does  not 
shrink  even  from  exposing  himself  to  impurity  in  order  to 
make  atonement  for  the  impure,  and  who  submits  even  to 
menial  service  in  order  to  wipe  away  the  impurity  he  has 
contracted  for  the  sake  of  men.  The  notion  of  guilt  is 
vitiated,  however,  by  its  being  referred  not  to  the  personal 
violation  of  duties,  but  merely  to  such  outward  acts  as — un- 
intentionally it  may  be  (as  in  the  case  of  Adrastus) — have  an 
unfortunate  result,  or  to  an  immoderate  prosperity  that  excites 
the  envy  of  the  gods  (as  in  the  Polycrates  myth).  It  is  not  a 
law-making  God  that  occupies  the  supreme  place  ;  fate  stands 
over  all  the  gods.  Moreover,  since  expiations  brought  no  real 
peace,  the  tendency  prevailed  in  heathen  life  either  to  seek 
forgetfulness  of  guilt  in  friA'olity,  and  to  relegate  to  Tartarus 
those  austere  and  gloomy  deities  that  remind  men  of  sin  and 
guilt,  or  to  disregard  altogether  the  inward  spiritual  discord, 
both  practically  and  theoretically. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  consciousness  of  guUt  and  punish- 
ment was  more  vivid  among  the  Helreios,  because  here  the 
law  was  set  up  in  an  objective  shape  ;  and  thus  the  religious 
and  moral  history  both  of  the  nation  as  a  whole  and  of  the 
individual  had  a  steadier  course.  Here  we  have  the  funda- 
mental moral  perception  that  guilt  is  the  debt  not  of  mis- 
fortune but  of  sin,  that  all  guilt  exposes  man  to  punishment,  and 


328     §  35(5.   COUNTEEACTION  OF  GOOD  AGAINST  EVIL.     PHILOSOPHY. 

that  evil  owes  its  existence  to  its  connection  with  wickedness, 
and  not  to  the  hostility  of  irresistible  powers  nor  to  a  deiov 
(pOovepov.  Besides,  the  keener  consciousness  of  sin  and  guilt 
among  the  Hebrews  was  met  by  a  divinely-appointed  provision 
for  atonement.  To  heathen  sacrifices  there  was  no  promise 
attached  ;  but  Hebrew  sacrifices,  in  virtue  of  their  divine 
institution,  vouchsafed  something  not  to  hope  merely  but  to 
faith ;  that  is  to  say,  when  the  offering  was  made,  the  peni- 
tent was  warranted  in  feeling  that  he  still  remained  a  citizen 
of  the  theocracy,  and  had  his  share  in  the  promise  for  the 
future. 

3.  In  the  heathen  world,  if  we  leave  political  regulations 
out  of  sight,  it  is  philosophy  that  corresponds  to  the  law  ;  she 
seeks  as  it  were  to  play  the  part  of  moral  lawgiver.  We 
see  this  in  Pythagoras,  Socrates,  Plato,  Aristotle,  and  Epicurus, 
the  Cynics  and  the  Stoics.  The  wise  man  is  the  Hellenic 
analogue  of  the  Messianic  Ideal.  This  doctrine  of  ivisdom  had 
even  something  ^^ro/j/ie^t'c  in  it,  especially  when  it  bore  a 
religious  character.  Thus  it  was  with  Plato,  to  whom  the 
closest  possible  assimilation  with  God  is  the  virtue  that  keeps 
the  State  together.  If,  now,  we  inquire  how  inward  personal 
goodness  is  to  be  produced,  then  it  is  evident  that  knowledge 
is  insufficient,  though  the  will  is  conceived  as  entirely 
dependent  upon  it,  for  ^povqat'^  is  not  within  the  reach  of  all. 
Hence  Plato  goes  back  in  true  Hellenic  fashion  to  nature  and 
natural  processes  ;  noble  children  are  to  be  begotten  by  bring- 
ing together  noble  parents,  and  he  would  make  political 
regulations  for  this  end.  Again,  and  this  is  still  more 
important,  he  says  in  the  Mcnon  that  virtue  can  neither  be 
learned  nor  acquired  by  practice,  but  must  be  given  deia 
fiolpa.  In  the  BcpuUic,  moreover,  he  says  that  the  appear- 
ance of  those  high,  wise,  and  just  persons,  on  whom,  according 
to  him,  depends  the  hope  of  a  regeneration  of  the  disordered 
commonwealth,  must  be  expected  as  a  "  gift  of  God."  As 
the  world  now  is — he  says  further  and  prophetically — were 
the  i^crfcdly  just  man  to  appear,  he  could  restore  faith  in 
righteousness  only  through  suffering  (even  scourging  and 
crucifixion  are  mentioned),  and  would  have  to  endure  the 
extremity  of  wrong  in  evincing  his  perfect  justice. 

The  Stoics,  moreover,  although  they  occupy  the  legal  stand- 


HEATHEN  ANALOGUES  OF  THE  MESSIAH.  329 

point  of  the  stage  of  right,  yet  cannot  deny  the  need  there  is 
of  bringing  the  good  out  of  its  abstract,  legal  form  into  a  more 
living  one  ;  so  they  too  draw  their  ideal  of  the  wise  man 
who  is  free  from  sin.  According  to  Chrysippus,  he  is  a 
king,  who  judges  all  things  and  is  himself  judged  by  no 
one  ;  according  to  Zeno,  he  is  a  priest,  made  so,  however, 
through  knowledge.  In  the  wise  man,  who  is  both  king 
and  priest,  they  have  produced  the  Hellenic  analogue  of  the 
image  of  the  Messiah.  But  where  this  wise  man  is  to  come 
from — on  that  point  the  Stoics  leave  us  in  perplexity.  They 
are  prevented  by  their  false  attitude  towards  religion,  by  their 
want  of  humility,  from  going  farther  still  and  postulating  a 
revelation.  They  endow  their  wise  man  with  the  sense  of 
absolute  freedom,  and  take  great  delight  in  drawing  a  picture 
of  him,  as  if  no  more  were  required  than  a  beautiful  ideal. 
Finally,  Stoicism  lacks  an  absolute  teleology  with  regard  to 
the  world ;  it  makes  the  history  of  the  world  run  in  a 
circle ;  when  the  world's  aeon  is  over,  it  is  resolved  again 
into  Zeus,  through  the  agency  of  fire.  Thus,  in  the  last 
resort,  a  fatalistic  necessity  rules  the  world.  It  rules  even 
the  wise  man — a  striking  contrast  to  that  sense  of  absolute 
freedom  with  which  he  is  credited.  The  reason  of  this  con- 
trast is  that  his  sense  of  freedom  has  only  a  pantheistic  basis. 
The  wise  man  calls  the  essence  of  his  being  the  "  god  in 
him  ; "  but  this  god,  like  those  of  polytheism  in  general, 
is  subject  to  fate,  and  is  no  better  in  this  respect  than  the 
deities  it  has  absorbed.  It  is  worthy  of  notice  that  the 
Hebrew  analogue  of  Stoicism,  namely  Pharisaism,  often 
arrived  at  fatalism  also  ;  for  when  God  is  thought  of  only 
as  the  World  -  law  or  its  representative,  then  as  the  law 
does  not  arise  out  of  His  own  essential  nature,  He  cannot 
be  absolute.  Above  Him  an  absolute  power  is  conceived, 
which  is  not  personal  and  free.  The  Eabbis  make  God  a 
student  of  the  law. 

4.  Through  the  religious  fact  of  the  giving  of  the  law,  the 
Hebrews  were  delivered  once  and  for  all  from  that  vacillation 
with  regard  to  moral  ideas  exhibited  by  the  Greeks,  who  are 
always  beginning  over  again  to  verify  and  state  them.  The 
religious  development  of  the  Hebrews  goes  on  steadily  within 
the    limits    of    the   law ;    while   their   sense   of  the   relation 


330  §  356.     COUNTERACTION  OF  GOOD  AGAINST  EVIL. 

between  God  and  man  is  firmly  maintained.  Pious  people 
living  under  the  law,  and  continuiug  to  practise  it,  were  of 
necessity  led  more  and  more  from  what  is  outward  to  what  is 
inward.  And  this  furthered  their  ideal  appropriation  of  the 
Iciw,  that  is  to  say,  their  religious  knowledge.  It  came  to  be 
recognised  that  good  intention  is  better  than  mere  external 
works ;  that  the  true  offering,  of  which  the  outward  one  is 
but  the  symbol,  is  that  inward  self-sacrifice  on  the  part  of 
man,  which  if  it  were  present  would  make  the  outward  super- 
fluous and  without  meaning.  The  ceremonial  law  and  other 
elements  of  the  Jewish  ritual  had  a  similar  effect.  But  there- 
with an  inner  conflict  sprang  up  with  the  whole  system  of 
symbolical  worship ;  the  longing  after  a  true  worship,  after 
reality,  came  to  maturity.  The  increasing  knowledge  of  the 
Jews  brought  them  pain,  a  deeper  consciousness  of  sin  and  of 
the  gulf  which  separated  them  from  God.  Thus  the  law 
fulfilled  its  end ;  it  quickened  their  consciousness  of  their 
need  of  redemption.  Faith  in  the  God  of  their  i'athers  now 
led  them  to  liopc  for  new  acts  of  God  in  the  future. 

The  substance  of  this  hope  is  as  follows :  {a)  As  God  wills 
that  His  glory  be  shown  forth,  so  He  wills  a  kingdom  of 
glory.  This  He  will  establish,  and  bring  to  pass  the  final 
consummation  through  the  Kingsliip  of  the  Messiah.  This 
hope  is  expressed  in  the  oldest  psalms  (ii.,  ex.)  and  prophets 
(Isaiah,  Micah).  (h)  It  was  recognised,  further,  that  Israel 
cannot  at  once  be  made  glorious  and  perfect,  that  the  kingdom 
of  God  cannot  appear  as  a  kingdom  of  glory  without  media- 
tion. True  and  permanent  kingship  can  only  spring  from 
inward  majesty,  that  is,  from  righteousness ;  and  righteousness 
manifests  itself  in  lowliness  and  renunciation.  The  people 
must  become  the  servant  of  Jehovah  in  the  full  true  sense ; 
then  only  will  the  sure  mercies  of  David  be  given  (Isa.  Iv.  3). 
Such  is  the  purport  of  Isaiah's  announcement  in  chap.  xl.  sq. 
There  the  people  is  at  first  described  as  the  servant  of 
Jehovah.  But  the  empirical  people  of  Israel  is  not  the 
servant  of  God ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  burdened  with  guilt, 
and  cannot  become  righteous  without  atonement.  It  can 
neither  wash  away  its  sin  nor  hear  it,  and  yet  the  perfection 
of  the  kingdom  depends  upon  the  people  becoming  holy  and 
reconciled  to  God.     Accordiugly,  prophecy  rises  to  the  con- 


THE  MESSIANIC  IDEA.  331 

ception  of  the  "  Branch  "  of  Jehovah,  of  whom  earlier  prophets 
had  already  spoken.  It  presents  Him  as  being  through  His 
personal  righteousness  the  manifested  archetype  of  the  people, 
who  represents  them  before  God,  and  becomes  the  mediator 
oi  forgiveness  and  conscious  recouciliation  (Isa.  liii.).  This  is 
the  Messianic  'priestliood.  Here  the  Messianic  hope  had  to 
concentrate  itself  in  the  most  definite  way  upon  one  single 
person,  who,  righteous  himself,  makes  the  rest  of  the  nation 
righteous,  and  gathers  them  together  into  his  kingdom,  the 
true  kingdom  of  God.  This  kingdom  is  now  pictured  in  the 
most  glowinsj  colours,  and  in  its  all-embracin<:f  and  redeeming 
majesty  (Isa.  lii.— Ivi.).  By  means  of  this  process,  which 
began  after  the  revelation  of  the  law,  Christianity  is  ideally 
foreshadowed,  while  on  the  subjective  side  man  is  made  ready 
to  receive  Christianity,  and  is  aroused  to  a  longing  desire 
for  it. 

5.  To  sum  lip.  The  condition  of  things  in  the  pre- 
Christian  world  makes  sufficiently  evident :  (1)  The  religious 
and  moral  helplessness  of  man,  or  his  need  of  redemption. 
Sin  and  guilt  require  atonement  before  everything  else.  And 
this  man  cannot  make  for  himself.  Nevertheless  (2)  humanity 
is  not  by  this  means  rendered  incapable  of  redemption,  either 
from  the  side  of  God  or  of  man.  On  the  human  side,  counter 
agencies  have  always  been  at  work  in  opposition  to  the  power 
of  sin ;  and  these  serve  to  prove  that  in  human  nature,  in 
spite  of  its  ruin,  a  point  was  still  left  at  which  the  Good 
could  enter,  when  it  appeared  in  the  form  of  a  divine  act. 
Previous  to  Christianity  also,  and  in  spite  of  sin,  progress  was 
made  in  many  departments  of  life  that  are  of  moral  value — 
in  politics,  art,  and  science.  Lawgivers  and  philosophers  gave 
partial  assistance  to  the  subjective  voice  of  conscience.  Even 
among  the  heathen  conscience  was  not  lifeless,  but  oppressed 
the  evil-doer  with  the  feelino;  of  gruilt  and  wretchedness.  But 
the  most  powerful  of  all  agencies  against  sin  were  the  institu- 
tions of  the  Old  Testament, — the  fixed,  objective  law,  and  the 
public  ordinances  that  were  established  in  accordance  with  it. 
But  history  also  affords  confirmation  of  what  we  have  already 
perceived  from  the  very  nature  of  the  case,  viz.  the  imperfection 
of  the  legal  stage  and  its  powerlessness  to  give  life.  It  was 
only  the  prophecy  of  new  and  higher  acts  of  God  that  upheld 


332       §  36.    NECESSITY  OF  THE  STAGE  OF  LOVE  BY  MEANS  OF 

humanity  in  its  moral  efforts  and  hopes.  Humanity  has 
never  been  left  altogether  without  prophecy ;  it  appeared  even 
in  heathenism,  it  had  its  chosen  seat  in  the  Hebrew  religion, 
and  it  formed  the  one  sustaining  element  amid  the  imperfec- 
tions of  the  legal  stage.  In  fine,  the  chief  thing  which  came 
to  maturity  before  Christianity  was  merely  the  knowledge  of 
sin  (Eom.  iii.  20),  the  sense  of  need,  the  heartfelt  yearning  for 
divine  help  and  for  the  divine  home  from  which  man  felt  he 
was  ejected  and  estranged.  In  this  way  man  was  prepared 
for  a  further  manifestation  on  the  part  of  God ;  that  is  to  say, 
his  need  of  redemption  was  intensified,  while  his  capacity  for 
it  had  now  become  complete. 


THIED    SECTION. 

THE  STAGE  OF  LOVE  OE  OF  THE  GOSPEL,  AS  THE  CONTENTS  OF 
THE  ETHICAL  WORLD-IDEAL  (§  31,  32). 

§36. 

[Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  ii.  §  62,  70,  iii.  §  89. — Ed.] 

The  legal  stage  being  imperfect  both  in  itself  (§  34,  34«) 
and  in  relation  to  evil  (§  35),  the  goal  of  God's 
creative  love  can  only  be  such  a  union  of  the  human 
will  with  the  divine  as  will  make  the  life  of  man  divine 
in  wisdom  and  holiness.  But  human  life  can  become 
divine  only  by  an  act  of  self-communication  on  the 
part  of  God,  that  is,  by  the  divine  life  becoming  human. 
The  will  of  God  is  therefore  wholly  directed  to  this  end, 
and  must  be  met  on  man's  part  by  a  receptivity  which 
responds  to  the  act  of  divine  love. 

1.  The  fundamental  fact  in  Christian  experience  is  tlie 
union  of  the  divine  and  human  life.  Accordingly,  Christian 
ethics  has  to  show  how  the  ethical  in  general  and  ethical 
science  are  inwardly  connected  with  this  which  is  at  once  the 
fundamental  idea  of  Christianity,  the  central  point  of  Christian 
doctrine,  and  the  central  fact  of  Christian  life.     And  this  can 


A  REVELATION  ON  THE  PART  OF  GOD.  333 

be  done  in  two  ways  ;  either  by  considering  human  needs  in 
themselves,  especially  as  affected  by  sin,  or  by  starting  from 
the  ethical  conception  of  God. 

2.  The  stage  of  perfect  morality,  which  is  of  necessity  kept 
in  view  from  the  very  first,  demands  that  the  divine  life 
become  human  in  order  that  human  life  may  become 
divine.  Even  the  Old  Testament  requires  that  heart  and  life 
be  at  one  with  God  (Gen.  v.  24,  vi.  9  ;  Ps.  li.  12  ;  Joel  iii.  1; 
Jer.  xxxi.  34).  The  doctrine  of  the  divine  image  in  which 
man  was  created  also  involves  the  same  truth  with  regard  to 
human  life  :  for  it  teaches  that  man  is  designed  to  recognise, 
of  his  own  fiee  will,  that  the  Good  which  resides  originally  in 
God  is  also  the  true  essence  of  his  own  nature,  that  he  is 
intended  to  enter  into  full  possession  of  it  as  a  free  yet 
morally  determined  being.  For  there  is  only  one  morality : 
the  original  of  it  is  in  God,  the  copy  of  it  is  in  man.  This  is 
also  the  meaning  of  1  Tim.  vi.  11,  according  to  which  we  are 
to  become  "men  of  God;"  and  of  2  Pet.  i.  3,  4,  where  it  is 
said  that  Christians  become  partakers  of  the  "  divine  nature." 
(Cf.  2  Cor.  i.  21,  22.)  Whatever  good  there  may  be  besides 
God  who  is  the  first  source  of  good,  it  cannot  exist  in  inde- 
pendence of  God ;  it  is  only  a  good  so  far  as  God  is  in  it  as 
a  quickening  power.  The  law  itself  is  not  satisfied  with 
separate,  single  acts  merely,  in  which  self-will  is  restrained, 
and  obedience  rendered  to  the  external  standard  of  the  law. 
When  taken  in  its  full  compass,  it  refers  not  only  to  what 
man  does,  but  to  what  he  is.  AVithin  it  is  the  image  of  the 
ideal  man,  of  man  as  he  is  designed  to  be,  although  it  is 
powerless  to  realize  that  ideal.  In  fact,  single  acts  done  with  a 
good  purpose  are  truly  good  only  when  they  are  the  expression 
of  a  will  that  loves  and  takes  pleasure  in  the  good  as  a  whole. 

Accordingly  it  comes  to  this :  good  must  not  merely  be 
wrung  by  force  as  it  were  from  the  natural  man ;  it  must  be 
the  product  of  a  character  that  is  good  through  and  through,  of  a 
leaning  towards  God  that  has  become  the  true,  higher  nature 
of  man.  For  it  is  not  good  fruits  that  make  a  good  tree,  but  a 
good  tree  that  brings  forth  good  fruits  (Matt.  vii.  1 7).  But  man, 
and  es^^ecially  sinful  man,  cannot  elicit  from  himself  goodness 
in  this  its  higher  spiritual  sense.  And  just  as  little  can  it  be 
supplied  to  him  by  creation.     It  could  not  be  given  him  to 


334  §  37.    NECESSITY  OF  THE  GOD-MAiST. 

begin  with,  for  then  there  would  have  been  no  possibility  of  a 
really  new  and  free  life  of  love  in  the  world,  distinct  from 
God,  although  not  independent  of  Him  (1  Cor.  xv.  45  ff.), 
Man  is  created  only  with  the  vov^,  receptiveness  for  the 
'TTvevfia.  Instead  of  overcoming  man  by  a  kind  of  natural 
force,  the  divine  love  and  its  communicableness  address  him 
as  a,  free  being.  They  ask  him,  as  it  were,  whether  he  will 
allow  himself  to  be  determined  by  God,  to  be  taken  possession 
of  and  swayed  by  the  Divine  Spirit,  whether  therefore  he  will 
admit  the  divine  spirit  of  love  (Eom,  viii.  1  ff.)  to  dwell 
within  him  as  an  inspiring  power,  a  higher  spiritual  nature. 

3.  FurUier,  just  as  man,  conscious  of  his  need,  yearns  for 
something  more  on  God's  part  than  what  He  has  given  in 
creation  and  the  law,  so  on  the  other  hand  the  divine  love  is 
not  satisfied  with  the  revelation  of  the  law.  For  the  law 
does  not  perfectly  reveal  the  goodness  of  God's  holy  love  nor 
its  communicableness.  It  is  only  a  communication  to  the 
intellect,  not  to  the  inmost  nature  and  will  of  man.  It  still 
stands  outside  of  these.  In  the  law  God  makes  demands ; 
He  gives  nothing.  But  God  intends  to  be  something  more  to 
the  world  than  mere  omnipotence  and  omnipresence ;  some- 
thing more  than  an  object  of  knowledge ;  something  more 
than  One  who  stands  over  against  the  world  in  the  attitude 
of  demand.  He  means  to  be  in  the  world  a  power  that 
both  loves  and  implants  love.  It  is  His  purpose  that  His 
cosmical  relation  to  the  world  should  become  an  ethical 
relation,  in  which  He  is  all  in  all  (1  Cor.  xv.  28).  The 
thorough  exposition  of  this  subject  belongs  to  Dogmatics. 

§  37.   The  Necessity  of  the  God-man  from  Ethical  Points  of 

View. 

[Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  ii.  §  G  2. — Ed.] 

The  revelation  of  God,  as  is  shown  in  Dogmatics,  is  consum- 
mated in  the  Incarnation,  which  gives  to  the  world  Him 
who  is  strictly  the  God-man.  From  ethical  principles 
also  it  follows  that  the  moral  perfection  both  of  the 
individual  and  of  the  world  as  a  whole  depends  npon  the 
realization  of  the  idea  of  God-manhood.     For  the  moral 


INSUFFICIENCY  OF  THE  LAW.  335 

principle  can  arrive  at  full  power,  or,  in  other  words, 
love  or  a  kingdom  of  love  be  realized  in  the  world,  only 
throngh  the  consummation  of  the  revelation  or  self-com- 
munication of  God.  The  God-man,  moreover,  must  be 
One,  and  must  be  unique,  both  in  Himself  and  in  rela- 
tion to  God,  as  well  as  in  the  essential  relation  which 
He  bears  to  humanity.  In  Him  there  must  dwell  a 
reconciling  and  perfecting  power  ;  uhe  power  of  establish- 
ing, through  the  Spirit  which  proceeds  from  Him,  the 
kingdom  of  God,  or  that  absolute  moral  organism  in 
which  is  realized  the  ideal  both  of  tlie  individual  and  of 
the  whole  world. 

1.  In  §  31  and  §  36  all  that  was  shown  was  that  the  moral 
life,  in  order  to  reach  perfection,  must  be  at  once  divine  and 
human.  No  conclusion,  however,  has  as  yet  been  arrived  at 
as  to  the  uniqueness  of  a  life  at  once  human  and  divine,  and 
none  as  to  the  ethical  significance  of  the  incarnation  of  God 
in  a  single  being,  who  is  both  God  and  man.  In  the  act  of 
God  implied  in  incarnation,  revelation  reaches  its  climax ; 
it  is  no  longer  a  mere  revelation,  for  love's  sake,  of  God's 
power,  wisdom,  and  justice ;  it  is  the  revelation  of  love  itself 
as  being  the  very  heart  of  God.  The  proof  from  ultimate 
principles  of  the  necessity  of  this  divine  act  belongs  to  the 
science  of  Dogmatics.  But  it  is  also  well  worth  our  while  to 
recognise  how  important,  from  an  ethical  point  of  view,  is  that 
form  of  the  self-communication  of  God  to  the  world  in  which 
the  perfect  life  of  love  appears  at  first  in  a  single  person,  that 
of  the  God-man,  and  then,  starting  from  Him  as  a  centre, 
diffuses  itself  by  a  moral  process  throughout  humanity. 

2.  It  is  true  that  the  law  is  a  revelation  not  merely  of  the 
divine  will  but  also  of  the  essential  nature  of  God,  But  that 
which  in  Him  is  most  essential,  viz.  His  love,  is  not  revealed 
in  the  law.  When  love  makes  a  demand,  it  does  not  yet 
appear  as  love  (not  even  when  it  is  love  that  it  demands). 
It  does  so  only  when  it  communicates  something,  nay  more, 
only  when  it  communicates  itself.  And  the  crown  of  the 
self-communication  of  God  to  the  world  is  just  the  incarna- 
tion.    By  a  personal  revelation  of  Himself  as  love,  God  can 


336  §  37.    NECESSITY  OF  THE  GOD-MAN. 

become  the  object  of  love,  and  raise  mankind  above  the  stage 
of  law. 

In  itself  the  law  cannot  be  an  object  of  love.  It  may  be 
revered,  but  it  cannot  be  loved.  Only  that  which  is  personal 
can  be  loved,  only  what  is  adapted  to  an  interchange  of  love, 
whereas  the  law  remains  cold  and  dead  to  the  human  heart 
(Gal.  iii.  2 1 ;  Eom.  vii.  6  f.).  Only  when  the  Good  appears 
not  merely  as  law,  but  in  the  form  of  a  person,  does  it  show 
that  it  seeks  to  communicate  itself,  and  only  then  does  it 
become  communicable.  Accordingly,  the  personal  life  of  Him 
who  is  the  God-man  exhibits  the  law  in  its  perfect  form ;  by 
His  fulfilment  of  it  He  brings  to  light  that  deep  principle  of 
love  on  which  it  is  based.  The  God-man,  as  being  in  Himself 
the  law  unveiled  and  fulfilled,  has  an  attractive  power  quite 
different  from  that  of  the  mere  <ypd/jifia.  The  archetype  is 
productive.  In  the  God-man,  the  Good  that  has  its  seat  in 
God  not  only  becomes  an  object  of  perception,  but  offers  to 
enter  into  a  fellowship  of  love  with  all  who  appropriate  it. 
And  thus  it  is  made  possible  for  every  one  who  does  so  to  live 
and  act  as  a  totality,  in  the  power  of  his  whole  nature  as 
inspired  by  the  spiritual  principle  of  love.  The  legal  stand- 
point always  tends  to  split  life  up  into  a  multiplicity  of  tasks, 
out  of  which  no  living  whole  can  be  formed ;  it  cannot  produce 
the  higher  spiritual  nature,  that  entire  bent  and  determination 
of  character  which  the  principle  of  love  alone  can  evoke  (Matt. 
vii.  17  ;  1  Cor.  xiii.).  On  the  legal  stage,  it  is  true,  man  is 
not  without  a  presentiment  of  what  is  wanting.  Still,  the 
longing  that  is  thereby  awakened  finds  satisfaction  nowhere 
but  in  Him  in  whom  the  love  of  God  appeared  in  intelligible 
form,  and  who  offers  Himself  to  faith  as  the  power  of  Good 
in  its  totality,  as  the  living  source  of  all  true  life,  of  a  life 
that  proceeds  from  Him,  and  may  be  received  by  all. 

3.  Further,  it  is  of  great  ethical  importance  to  observe  that 
human  freedom,  which  is  the  indispensable  characteristic  of 
moral  progress,  cannot  be  preserved  in  the  transition  to  the 
third  stage  unless  by  revelation  reaching  its  completion  in  the 
incarnation.  If  humanity  were  to  be  led  up  to  the  highest 
stage  wholly  by  means  of  an  inward  spiritual  operation  (the 
"  ideal  Christ "  or  the  "  God-spirit "),  it  could  not  maintain 
j)erfect  freedom  in  relation  to  the  divine  act.     Man  could  not 


FAITH  IN  CHRIST  MORALLY  NECESSARY.  337 

resist  a  merely  inward  spiritual  agency ;  for  in  order  to  act 
upon  him,  it  must  already  have  inwardly  determined  his  Ego, 
— his  feelings,  disposition,  and  intelligence, — and  thus  his 
freedom  would  be  more  or  less  impaired.  An  external  revela- 
tion, on  the  contrary,  presents  itself  first  of  all  to  perception, 
and  taking  its  stand  here,  on  neutral  ground  as  it  were,  main- 
tains its  objectivity  over  against  the  Ego  in  such  a  way  that 
the  will  remains  free  with  regard  to  it,  and  can  therefore 
freely  appropriate  the  revelation  that  is  giv  ^n.  The  historical 
revelation  in  the  God-man  is  mediated  first  of  all  through  the 
senses ;  it  offers  itself  to  objective  perception,  and  the  Ego 
maintains  its  freedom  over  against  the  object  presented  to  it.^ 
4.  Again,  when  we  decide  to  accept  the  God-man  it  is  not 
an  act  of  caprice  on  our  part,  but  an  act  which  is  morally 
warranted  and  even  morally  necessary.  This  arises  from  the 
uniqueness  of  the  God-man;  for  in  Him  dwells  the  fulness  of 
the  Godhead,  and  only  through  Him  can  the  highest  moral  stage 
he  reached.  Here,  indeed,  it  might  be  objected  that  the  mani- 
festation of  God  in  one  man  is  in  contradiction  with  the  very 
thing  that  is  to  be  revealed,  since  God  is  infinite  and  cannot 
reveal  His  fulness  in  a  single  being,  subject  to  the  limitations 
of  sense.  If  we  say,  then,  that  revelation  must  be  consum- 
mated in  the  person  of  the  God-man,  does  this  not  necessarily 
introduce  confusion  into  the  true  idea  of  God  ?  To  this  it 
may  be  replied,  that  if  the  infinitude  of  God  meant  indeter- 
minateness,  then  a  revelation  of  Him  in  the  world  of  sense 
would  be  a  contradiction.      But  the  infinitude  of  God  is  not 

1  The  necessity  for  an  objective  revelation  is  also  evident  from  the  following 
considerations  :  God  cannot  be  comprehended  by  finite  creatures  if  He  is  only  a 
supersensible  and  omnipresent  Being,  if  He  does  not,  in  Luther's  words,  become 
"  inclosed  for  us  "  in  a  definite  revelation,  wliich  the  spirit  of  man  can  apprehend 
objectively;  "  if  He  does  not  summon  us  to  some  definite  place  where  we  are 
sure  to  find  and  have  Him."  Therefore  the  eternal  Word  clothes  Himself  in  an 
outward  manifestation  in  space  and  time ;  and  the  gospel  is  the  proclamation  or 
preaching  of  the  Word  become  flesh.  The  necessity  of  the  God-man  for  the  con- 
summation of  revelation  is  in  harmonj',  therefore,  with  the  universal  principle 
expressed  in  Rom.  x.  17.  Faith  does  not  arise  of  itself  or  altogether  from  within. 
It  is  an  important  maxim  both  for  ethics  and  dogmatics,  that  the  outward  word 
is  necessary.  For  man's  appropriation  of  the  divine  influence  can  preserve  a 
moral  form  in  no  other  way  than  by  the  revelation  of  God  entering  into  the 
finitude  and  individuality  which  space  and  time  impose,  and  by  its  becoming  a 
historical  power  alongside  of  others,  so  that  man  can  maintain  his  freedom 
towards  it — that  is  to  say,  can  reject  or  acquiesce  in  and  accept  it. 


I 


3:38       §  37.    NECESSITY  OF  THE  GOD-:\rAX.       HIS  UNIQUENESS. 

indeterminateness,  aireipov.  On  the  contrary,  it  is  intensive, 
it  belongs  to  His  ethical  nature,  and  being  such,  it  is  quite 
compatible  with  determinateness.  And  a  specific  ethical 
character  can  certainly  be  revealed.  The  world,  moreover, 
and  man  especially,  is  fitted  to  express  not  only  what  is  finite, 
Ijut  also  what  is  of  infinite  value,  viz.  the  wisdom  and  love  ot 
God.  Human  nature  has  been  created  with  special  reference 
to  the  perfect  revelation  of  love,  that  is,  to  perfect  self-com- 
munication on  the  part  of  God. 

Further,  if  God  by  becoming  incarnate  in  a  single  person 
appears  to  confine  Himself  within  limits,  and  thus  to  contra- 
dict His  own  universality,  yet,  on  the  other  hand,  it  must  be 
remembered  that  this  revelation  includes  all  men  in  its  refer- 
ence. It  is  true  that  Christ  is  only  a  single  individual,  but 
He  has  a  universal  significance.  Regarded  objectively.  He  is 
the  manifested  love  of  God  to  mankind  in  general;  while,  at 
the  same  time,  regarded  subjectively,  or  as  a  human  being, 
He  is  the  love  that  embraces  the  whole  of  humanity.  On  the 
legal  stage  what  was  wanting  was  a  character  wholly  deter- 
mined and  animated  by  love.  Accordingly  Christ  is  unique 
for  this  reason,  that  as  He  offers  Himself  to  all  alike,  so  all 
see  in  Him  the  centre  of  humanity,  since  He  is  the  man  in 
whom  the  divine  love  has  appeared  in  historical  shape.  When 
the  idea  of  the  God-man  is  realized,  something  of  eternal  and 
universal  worth  for  the  whole  of  humanity  is  given,  and  hence 
the  God-man,  the  Bevrepo^;  'ABdfi,  is  wholly  unique.  A  repe- 
tition of  the  act  in  which  the  idea  of  God-manhood  has  been 
realized  would  be  superfluous,  and  would  disturb  the  unity 
of  the  world. 

But  now,  what  is  the  relation  which  different  individuals 
bear  to  this  one  God-man,  this  productive  archetype  ?  The 
life  of  love,  indeed,  appears  in  a  multiplicity  of  individual 
forms,  but  love  is  essentially  one  and  the  same.  Since  the 
God-man  reveals  the  divine  love  in  the  form  of  a  person,  it 
follows  that  all  men  stand  in  essentially  the  same  relation  to 
Him  to  begin  with  ;  all  alike  need  Him,  and  are  capable  of 
receiving  Him.  In  like  manner,  He  stands  in  essentially  the 
same  relation  to  all.  He  has  not  a  peculiar  afiinity  to  certain 
persons,  as  if  He  were  in  a  special  sense  their  archetype,  and 
the  source  of  a  higher  life  in  tlicni ;  for  this  would  imply  that 


FAITH  NOT  AN  ACT  OF  CAPEICE,  339 

He  was  not  so  closely  and  essentially  related  to  others.  But 
although  He  is  a  single  human  individual  as  other  men  are, 
yet  He  is  also  unique.  For  as  He  devotes  Himself  to  all  alike, 
so  all  find  in  Him  the  objective  historical  centre  of  their 
higher  life.  He  is  the  central  man  among  men,  since  in  Him 
the  divine  love,  that  invisible  centre  of  the  world,  has  appeared 
in  history  in  a  personal  form,  and  become  the  personal  head 
of  humanity.  From  this  it  follows  again  as  a  matter  of  course 
that  only  one  man  such  as  He  can  appear.  He  is  the  true, 
predestined  Head  of  humanity. 

Thus,  too,  it  becomes  evident  how  faith  in  Him  can  be 
demanded  of  every  one  ;  in  other  words,  it  becomes  clear  that 
the  vofio^  TTLdTewi  in  Him  expresses  a  duty  which  is  just  as 
true  and  essential  as  any  other.  Faith  in  Him  must  be 
required  as  a  matter  of  universal  obligation  or  duty.  It  may 
be  said,  though  with  no  real  force,  "  Faith  is  an  act  of 
caprice  ;  it  cannot  be  exercised  knowingly  and  consciously  as 
a  duty,  since  that  only  can  be  called  a  moral  duty  which  has 
an  essential  connection  with  our  moral  nature  and  constitution. 
But  the  God-man  has  onh'  an  accidental  position  with  regard 
to  men,  a  position  that  is  conditioned  by  the  accidental  fact 
of  sin.  Consequently,  when  we  put  faith  in  Him  we  do  not 
act  morally,  but  only  from  caprice,  and  our  act  therefore  is 
mixed  up  with  sin,  or  is  mere  blind  submission  to  the  autho- 
rity of  the  Church,  just  as  the  mission  of  the  God-man  is 
itself  due  to  the  hencplaciium  of  God,  and  is  therefore  an  act 
of  caprice."  This  objection,  which,  indeed,  would  strictly 
exclude  the  God-man  from  the  moral  organism  which  has 
existed  in  the  thought  and  will  of  God  from  all  eternity,  is 
refuted  by  the  fact  that  the  bond  which  connects  us  with  the 
God-man  is  not  anything  accidental  to  human  nature.  On 
the  contrary,  God  had  in  view  the  moral  perfection  of  man  at 
the  creation,^  and  this  His  final  purpose  cannot  possibly  be 
accomplished  by  a  mere  revelation  of  law,  but  only  by  the 
highest  revelation  of  all,  namely,  one  of  love  (§  34).  And  as  we 
have  already  seen,  such  a  revelation  cannot  at  first  be  wholly 
and  simply  an  internal  one,  but  must  take  objective  shape  in  the 
God-man.  Human  nature,  moreover,  was  constituted  at  creation 
in  such  a  way,  that,  in  the  event  of  sin  arising,  we   can  be 

^  Col.  i.  13-20  ;  Eph.  iii.  9  f.,  i.  9  f. 


340  §  37.    NECESSITY  OF  THE  GOD-MAN. 

redeemed  by  the  God-man  ;  in  that  case  we  are  referred  to 
Him  for  deliverance,  and  have  the  power  to  receive  Him. 
For  from  the  uniqueness  of  His  person  the  following  results 
may  at  once  be  derived.  Since  there  is  in  Him  universal 
ethical  power,  sufficient  for  all,  and  since  His  relation  to 
all  men  is  not  a  mere  accidental,  but  an  essential  one,  so 
when  sin  arises  He  can  represent  them  heforc  God,  can  make 
atonement  for  and  perfect  them.  And  not  only  has  He  the  power 
thus  to  reconcile  and  redeem  men,  it  is  His  essential  vocation 
so  to  do,  not  a  vocation  which  He  enters  upon  arbitrarily. 

5.  Further,  Christ  is  also  He  through  whom  the  kingdom  of 
God  really  becomes  the  world's  goal.  His  loving  self-surrender 
to  mankind  awakens  the  faith  and  self-surrender  of  mankind 
towards  Him ;  men  become  willing  to  be  determined  by 
His  spirit  and  will  alone,  and  to  be  filled  with  His  all- 
sufticient  power ;  and  thus  there  begins  to  exist,  both  in  the 
absolute  and  secondary  spheres,  a  community  of  love  of  which 
He  is  the  organizing  principle.  Believers  now  recognise  tliat 
in  Him  they  are  united  both  to  God  and  to  each  other  ;  they 
begin  to  have  a  far  higher  idea  of  what  community  is,  and  to 
realize  it  in  a  far  higher  shape  than  what  appeared  in  the 
natural  associations  of  the  first  stage,  or  the  communities  that 
arose  on  the  stage  of  right.  Believers  being  united  to  Jesus 
have  Him  as  their  centre — in  a  historical  and  not  merely 
transcendental,  but  also  in  an  ideal  and  not  merely  an  exter- 
nal sense  ;  they  find  in  Him  their  true  unity,  and  yield  them- 
selves to  be  moulded  by  Him  ;  and  thus  they  now  form  a 
community  of  love,  recognising  that  they  are  all  members  of 
one  organism,  of  that  true  humanity  of  which  the  head  is 
Christ.  Now  no  such  organic  unity  could  result  from  a  mere 
immanent  operation  of  the  Divine  Spirit.  In  that  case  the 
unity  that  existed  would  be  wholly  inward  and  beyond 
experience,  residing  either  in  human  nature  itself,  if  we  take 
the  Pelagian  view,  or  in  God  ;  it  would  remain  behind  a  veil, 
and  never  be  disclosed  to  consciousness.  But  the  God-man, 
who  takes  possession  of  individual  believers  and  brings  them 
into  organic  connection  with  each  other,  is  the  real,  historic 
head  of  true  humanity,  the  humanity  which  corresponds  with 
the  ultimate  destiny  of  man  ;  He  remains  indissolubly  bound 
up  with  mankind  even  after  He  has  triumphed  over  sin  and 


HIS  ABSOLUTE  AND  PERMANENT  SIGNIFICANCE.  341 

death,  and  men  recognise  their  unity  in  Him  as  an  objective 
factor  in  the  world's  history. 

"When  once  the  absohite  stage  of  religion  and  morality  has 
been  reached,  it  never  gives  place  to  any  other.  For  the 
God-man  does  not  occupy  in  it  a  merely  accidental  position, 
such  as  is  held  in  other  religions  by  their  founders  and  pro- 
phets (Moses,  for  instance).  In  it,  on  the  contrary,  the  divine 
principle  of  mediation,  which  has  taken  historical  form  in  the 
person  of  the  God-man,  ever  remains  an  integral  element. 
Were  Christ  to  cease  to  be  of  permanent  significance,  it  would 
follow  that  even  the  absolute  religion  is  awaiting  another  reli- 
gion to  which  it  will  give  place,  and  that  even  that  stage 
which  exhibits  the  principle  of  morality  in  absolute  perfection 
will  yet  cease  to  exist. 

6.  According  to  the  exposition  that  has  been  given,  the 
God-man  is  the  means  by  which  the  world  attains  its  con- 
summation. But  at  the  same  time  He  is  more  than  a 
means.  In  order  to  be  a  means  in  this  absolute  sense  He 
must  be  love  itself  made  manifest  in  a  personal  form.  Xow 
love,  although  it  may  make  itself  a  means,  yet  contains  also 
its  end  in  itself,  and  is  even  an  absolute  end  in  itself.  Hence 
we  must  not  stop  short  with  regarding  the  God-man  as  a 
means  merely,  as  a  theophany  given  wholly  for  ends  that  lie 
outside  itself  (Scripture  speaks  of  a  glorification  of  the  person 
and  personal  dignity  of  Jesus).  While  He  is  all  this  to 
humanity.  He  is  also  in  Himself  a  good  within  the  world 
which  the  world  cannot  want ;  He  is  its  crown  and  its  shrine. 
He  is  the  full  manifestation  of  morality,  inasmuch  as  in  Him 
we  have  the  unity  of  law,  virtue  and  the  supreme  good.  On 
the  legal  stage  these  three  still  stand  outside  each  other.  But 
as  the  God-man  is  the  law  unveiled  and  fulfilled,  so  in  Him, 
too,  we  see  virtue  and  virtuous  energy  in  a  f)ersonal  form.  As 
love  manifesting  itself  jDersonally  and  in  union  with  God,  He 
is  the  absolutely  virtuous  man,  the  virtue  of  our  race. 

Moreover,  besides  being  a  good  in  Himself,  He  is  also  the 
beginning  of  the  existence  of  the  chief  good  in  the  world,  both 
in  its  subjective  and  its  objective  form ;  He  is  the  fertile 
principle  of  its  realization  in  humanity.  Thus  in  Him  the 
highest  moral  stage  is  realized  in  a  personal  shape.  The  God- 
man  is  necessary  both  as  an  end  in  Himself  and  as  a  means 


342  §  37.    NECESSITY  OF  THE  GOD-MAK 

for  the  realization  of  the  kiugdoni  of  God,  of  which  He  is  the 
head  ;  that  is  to  say,  He  is  necessary  for  the  consummation 
of  the  divine  order  of  the  world.  [For  we  see  that  only 
through  Him  can  humanity  attain  to  the  highest  stage,  whether 
we  take  sin  into  account  or  look  at  the  matter  apart  from 
sin  altogether. — Ed.] 

7.  The  fundamental  idea  of  which  an  exposition  has  been 
given  appears  in  primitive  Christian  thought  (Col.  i.  13-20  ; 
Eph.  iii.  9  f.,  i.  9  f,).  It  has  also  been  accepted  by  great 
theologians  in  every  age,  such  as  Iren8eus,  Tertullian,  Athan- 
asius,  Gregory  of  Nyssa ;  while  in  addition  to  many  in  the 
Middle  Ages,  Luther,  Melanclithon,  Calvin,  Brentz,  and 
Osiander  present  clear  traces  of  it.^  Here  we  would  make 
only  two  additional  observations. 

(1.)  Tlie  absoluteness  of  Christian  Etliics  cannot  he  maintained 
sinless  toe  recognise  that  the  person  of  Christ  is  and  continues 
to  be  essential  to  the  absoluteness  of  the  Christian  religion. 

(2.)  What  makes  many  hesitate  to  assent  to  the  foregoing 
proposition  is  the  idea  that  it  would  make  the  incarnation, 
which  is  the  highest  act  of  God's  free  love,  not  an  act  of  free 
will  at  all,  but  of  physical  necessity.  But  since  free  love  is 
something  quite  different  from  caprice,  and  is  yet  in  itself  a 
moral  though  not  a  physical  necessity,  this  scruple  is  easily 
removed  by  the  following  considerations.  When  God,  out  of 
love  and  for  the  ends  of  love,  wills  the  existence  of  the  world, 
there  is  here  no  physical  necessity,  since  the  world  adds 
nothing  to  the  divine  cf)vac<;,  and  the  latter  cannot  act  by  itself. 
But,  at  the  same  time,  neither  is  there  anything  of  the 
nature  of  accident  or  caprice.  Whatever  is  in  harmony  with 
the  divine  love  is  good,  and  so  morally  necessary.  jSTow  we 
only  proceed  farther,  as  we  must  do  to  be  consistent,  and  say 
— if  God  had  not  willed  the  world,  then  in  that  case  the  in- 
carnation would  in  no  wise  be  necessary ;  but  since  the  free 
will  of  God  does  will  the  world,  it  must  do  so  teleologically  ; 
that  is  to  say,  it  must  keep  in  view  the  final  consummation  of 
the  world  as  its  goal.  Hence  it  must  also  will  the  existence  of 
the  God-man,  without  whom  that  consummation  is  impossible. 

1  Cf.  my  Doctrine  of  the  Person  of  Christ,  Div.  II.  vol.  iii.  p.  248  et  secj. 
(transl.),  where  the  objections  are  discussed  tliat  have  been  brought  against 
certain  forms  in  which  this  doctrine  has  been  stated. 


SECOND    PART. 

THE  GOOD  AS  EEALIZED  IN  CHRISTIANITY. 

§  38.  Sijllahus.     [Cf.  §  5.  3,  4.— Ed.] 

Division  I.  Christ  the  Incarnate  Good,  or  the  Eealization, 
in  principle,  of  Morality  in  IMankind. 

Division    II.  The  Christian  Personality. 

Division  III.  The  Organized  World  of  Christian  Morality,  or 
the  Moral  Commnnity  of  the  Kingdom  of 
God. 

Note. — Communities  and  individuals  have  already  been  con- 
sidered in  important  and  fundamental  aspects — viz.  in  the 
forms  which  they  take  on  the  first  stage  or  stage  of  nature,  as 
well  as  in  those  which  they  assume  on  the  stage  of  right.  At 
present  they  have  to  be  examined  from  the  point  of  view  of  the 
second  or  spiritual  creation,  in  which  whatever  was  true  in  the 
earlier  stages  is  preserved  and  carried  forward  to  completion. 

FIRST     DIVISION. 

CHRIST  THE  GOD-MAN,  AS  THE  REALIZATION,  IN  PRINCIPLE,  OF 
MORALITY  IN  MANKIND. 

§  39. 

In  Christ  we  have  the  perfect  unity  of  the  three  fundamental 
forms  of  morality,  viz.  the  law,  virtue,  and  the  chief 
good ;  so  that  He  and  He  alone  is  the  principle  that 
has  power  to  bring  these  into  unity  and  coalescence. 
Thus  Christ  is  (1)  the  personal  law  of  foAth  and  life — 
or  the  personal  conscience  of  humanity.  (2)  He  is 
absolutely  pure  and  all-embracing  virtue;  and  as  such 
He   has  become  the  2'^crsonal  satisfaction  for   our  race 


344       §  39.    CHRIST  THE  REALIZATION  OF  PERFECT  MORALITY. 

towards  God,  a  satisfaction  that  is  offered  to  the  faith  of 
reconciled  humanity.  (3)  As  King  of  Love  He  is  the 
beginning  of  the  Kingdom  of  God,  endowed  with  infinite 
fulness  of  power. 

1.  Since  Christ,  as  belonging  to  mankind,  is  the  living  law 
or  conscience  of  humanity,  the  virtue  of  our  race,  and  its 
fundamental  moral  good,  ethical  Christology  forms  the  comple- 
ment to  the  doctrine  of  the  Offices  of  Christ.  When  these 
three  elements  remain  separate,  it  is  a  mark  of  moral  imper- 
fection, if  not  of  sin  itself.  Their  union  is  necessary  to  moral 
perfection,  and  involves  perfect  knowledge,  a  perfect  heart, 
and  perfect  energy  of  will.  It  is  true  that  we  would  have  no 
right  to  take  this  ethical  view  of  the  person  of  Christ  if  He 
were  a  theophany  merely,  and  not  One  who  becomes  man  in 
a  true,  personal  and  moral  sense — if,  therefore.  His  ethical 
worth  were  not  something  which,  while  depending  ultimately 
on  an  act  of  God,  He  nevertheless  gained  through  conflict  and 
development.  But  such  is  the  case  according  to  the  Biblical 
view  (Heb.  ii.  17  f.,  iv.  15,  v.  7  f.).  His  moral  perfection  is 
borne  witness  to  by  all  His  disciples  (1  Pet.  ii.  22  ;  2  Cor. 
V.  21;  Phil.  ii.  8,  9;  Eom.  v.  19  ;  Heb.  ii.  10,  iv.  15, 
vii.  2G);  by  His  own  declarations — as  when  He  asserts  that 
He  is  the  Eedeemer,  and  therefore  One  who  does  not  Himself 
stand  in  need  of  redemption  (Matt.  v.  17  ;  John  viii.  29,  46  ; 
Matt.  XX.  28,  xviii.  20),  and  that  He  is  the  judge  of  the 
world  (John  iii.  36  ;  Matt,  xxv.)  ;  and  finally,  by  the  impres- 
sion which  the  image  of  Christ  makes  at  all  times,  and  the 
power  which  continually  flows  from  Him.  Let  us  now  con- 
sider one  by  one  the  three  points  which  have  been  mentioned. 

PIEST   SECTION". 

CHRIST  THE  PERFECT  REVELATIOX  OF  THE  DIVINE  LAW. 
§40. 

Christ  is  the  end  of  the  law,  inasmuch  as  He  perfects  it.  And 
He  perfects  the  law  through  His  being  the  will  of  God 
unveiled  and  fulfilled.      Thus  He  is,  in  His  own  person, 


§  40.    CHRIST  THE  REVELATION  OF  THE  LAW.  345 

the  perfect  law  of  life  and  faith,  permanently  incorpo- 
rated with  humanity  ;  He  is  the  conscience  of  mankind. 
[Cf.  System  oj  Christian  Doctrine,  vol.  iii.  §  111. — Ed.] 

1.  The  authority  which  we  here  ascribe  to  Christ  as  the 
"  lex  viva  prasensque,"  can  only  belong  to  Him  if  He  is  not 
merely  a  man  like  ourselves  but  a  revelation  of  the  Father ; 
not  only  a  man  furnished  with  divine  powers,  but  He  within 
whose  person  the  Godhead  dwelt.  He  is  quite  different  from 
other  religious  teachers.  We  must  not  regard  Moses,  e.g.,  as 
if  it  were  his  person  that  laid  on  us  the  obligation  to  obey  his 
precepts.  But  Christ  is  the  revelation  of  the  Father  in  such 
a  way,  that  while  He  is  a  man  related  to  us  and  approachable 
by  us,  He  at  the  same  time  has  the  knowledge  of  truth  as  His 
own  personal  possession.  Thus  His  knowledge  is  that  of  the 
free  Son  of  God.  It  is  the  archetype  of  ours  and  communicable 
to  us ;  and  more,  it  is  the  exemplar  of  ours,  since  Christ  by 
self-discipline  increased  in  knowledge  and  wisdom,  and  abiding 
in  firm  and  faithful  union  with  God  became  the  conscience  of 
humanity. 

2.  Now  the  perfect  law  is  a  lavj  of  life  and  of  faith 
(§  31.  3).  Christ  has  become  both  of  these,  since  (to  use 
Dr.  Schmid's  ^  apt  expression)  He  has  perfectly  "  unveiled 
and  fulfilled  "  the  deKruia  of  God  by  His  teaching  and  His 
life. 

(a)  He  is  the  km  of  life  for  us ;  for  He  unveils  tlie  true 
will  of  God  by  His  teaching  and  life. 

(a)  By  His  teaching.  The  multiplicity  of  precepts  enjoined 
in  the  old  covenant  are  gathered  up  by  Christ  into  the  unity 
of  the  single  commandment  of  love,  which  embraces  all  the 
powers  of  man  (Matt.  xxii.  37  ff.,  v.  44;  Luke  x.  27  f.). 
He  thus  gives  man  a  deeper  sense  of  what  morality  really 
is,  and  opens  ^^p  in  him  the  fountain  of  free,  personal,  moral 
knowledge  (John  viii.  32),  in  order  that  his  moral  obedience 
may  be  rendered  free  by  his  direct  apprehension  of  moral 
truth  (John  iv.  14,  vii.  38  f.,  xv.  15).  The  unity  of  Christ's 
law  gives  a  united  direction  to  moral  effort  (John  xiii.  34). 
Hence  to  Christ  no  work  is  good  unless  accompanied  by  a 

1  Quceritiir  de  notione  legis  in  theolorjia  Christianorum  morali  rite  con- 
etituenda,  1832. 


346  §  40,    CHRIST  THE  KEVELATION  OF  THE  LAW. 

t^ood  intention  and  disposition ;  He  rejects  a  mere  mechanical 
form  of  religion  (cf.  what  He  says  concerning  sacrifice  and 
the  Sabbath,  Matt.  ix.  13  ;  Mark  ii.  27).  Nor  is  an  inten- 
tion good  unless  accompanied  by  a  good  work  (Matt.  xv.  1  ff., 
Corban).  But  to  Him  those  works  alone  are  good  which 
spring  from  the  totality  of  a  good  moral  character  (Matt, 
vii.  17). 

(/8)  By  His  life.  Christ  unveils  the  law  of  life  perfectly 
and  effectively  by  the  example  and  pattern  which  He  affords, 
or  in  other  words,  He  unveils  it  by  fulfilling  it.  By  this 
means  the  law  remains  no  longer  in  an  impersonal  form,  a 
cold,  dead  fypufi/xa ;  but  as  personal,  holy  love,  it  assumes  an 
attractive  and  lovely  shape  (John  i.  14).  Christ  encourages 
us  to  fulfil  the  law  by  showing  that  it  can  be  fulfilled,  and 
thus  establishing  our  belief  in  its  perfect  validity.  It  might 
Ije  supposed,  indeed,  that  since  He  was  the  Son  of  God,  while 
we  are  the  children  of  the  sinful  race  of  men,  we  cannot  take 
Him  as  a  pattern  for  ourselves,  nor  can  He  be  a  guarantee  to 
us  that  the  law  can  be  fulfilled.  But  to  this  we  reply,  that  if 
He  had  been  sinless,  holy,  and  just,  not  from  His  connection 
with  God  but  in  His  mere  power  as  a  man.  He  would  not  in 
that  case  be  a  pattern  for  us,  but  a  judgment  against  us. 
Besides,  He  would  be  an  incomprehensible  phenomenon  in 
the  midst  of  sinful  humanity.  But  He  is  no  such  pheno- 
menon as  this  ;  for  while  man  He  is  also  Son  of  God,  the 
revelation  of  the  Father,  in  whom  God  has  made  a  new 
communication  of  Himself  to  humanity.  Moreover,  the 
revelation  given  in  Him  is  intended  for  all  men,  in  spite  of 
sin  and  as  a  gift  of  free  grace.  That  is  to  say,  Christ  is  not 
only  the  law  of  life,  but  also  and  before  everything  else  the 
law  of  faith,  and  as  such  He  can  be  a  pattern  for  men. 

(h)  The  law  of  faith.  Christ  unveils  the  whole  counsel 
and  will  of  God  from  its  very  foundation.  He  does  not, 
therefore,  reveal  the  divine  will  merely  as  holy  and  just  and 
so  making  demands  upon  us,  but  also  in  its  pardoning  and 
sanctifying  character,  and  so  as  bestowing  something  upon  us. 
The  divine  law  of  life,  made  manifest  in  Him,  becomes  fruitful 
and  efficacious  only  by  His  being  at  the  same  time  the  law  of 
faith.  And  this  He  is,  because  by  perfectly  fulfilling  the 
demands  of  the  divine  deXrjfia  He  has  won  in  His  own  person 


CHRIST  THE  LAW  OF  FAITH.  347 

a  good  for  humanity,  which  man  has  to  receive  by  faith,  and 
in  which  the  power  of  reconciliation  and  sanctification  dwells. 
This  good  is  not  merely  something  which  He  holds  up  to  view 
and  instructs  us  about,  but  something  which  He  has  to  win  in 
His  own  person  as  mediator  (cf.  Second  Section).  If  He  were 
merely  a  teacher  and  moral  lawgiver,  His  person  would  have 
only  an  accidental  significance,  like  that  of  Moses  or  one  of 
the  prophets.      But  Christ  is  what  He  teaches. 

3.  Christ,  moreover,  though  He  is  an  individual  man,  can 
be  the  all-embracing  law  for  all  men.  The  form  of  personality 
is  not  a  limitation  for  love;  it  is  rather  the  means  by  wdiich 
love  manifests  itself.  It  is  in  the  nature  of  love  to  take  up 
its  abode  in  individuals ;  and  the  divine  good  comes  to  actual 
historical  existence  in  the  person  of  Him  who  on  His  human 
side  possesses  every  ret[uisite  for  its  manifestation.  Thus  He 
is  the  Son  of  man  ;  He  is  of  universal  significance,  and  has 
the  same  relation  to  all.  It  is  a  duty  incumbent  upon  the 
universal  human  conscience  to  acknowledge  Christ  as  the  law 
of  faith  and  life  ;  for  he  is  the  objective  conscience  of  humanity, 
its  ethical  truth  and  wisdom.  Thus  it  is  possible  for  iis  to 
put  faith  in  Him,  as  an  act  of  conscience  and  not  of  blind 
caprice.  The  law  given  in  conscience,  which  also  has  its 
origin  in  the  Logos  (John  i.  4,  v.  39),  is  meant  to  act  as  a 
"  7ratSa7&)70?  "  (Gal.  iii.  24).  In  other  words,  by  recognising 
itself  in  Christ,  and  even  finding  in  Him  its  own  essential 
truth,  it  thus  forms  a  stepping-stone  to  faith,  which  confides 
itself  entirely  to  Him  (John  vii.  17).  The  eternal  Logos  uses 
conscience  as  a  means  of  drawing  men  to  Him  who  became 
flesh;  in  the  first  revelation,  that,  viz.,  which  was  made  in  the 
natural  conscience  of  man,  the  second  and  perfecting  one  was 
kept  in  view  ;  while  conversely,  the  latter  links  itself  on  to 
the  former.  It  is  one  and  the  same  law  which  has  its  founda- 
tion in  conscience  and  is  perfectly  revealed  in  Christ,  and 
through  Him  it  comes  to  universal  realization. 

This  fact  must  give  an  ethical  character  to  the  whole 
doctrine  of  the  appropriation  of  salvation.  It  is  in  direct 
opposition  to  that  kind  of  faith  which  is  satisfied  with  mere 
intellectual  motives,  with  acts  that  spring  from  the  head  or 
understanding  alone — the  faith  of  Eationalism  and  of  pseudo- 
orthodoxy   with  its    intellectual    legalism.         On    the    other 


348  §  41.    CHRIST  THE  ALL-EMBEACING  VIRTUE. 

hand,  the  true  doctrine  of  Christ  as  the  law  of  faith  and  life 
is  also  opposed  to  the  error  of  Antinomicmism.  Antinomian- 
ism  takes  faith  as  constituting  in  itself  the  solution  of  the 
entire  moral  problem,  and  for  this  reason, — that  in  it  a  new 
and  all-powerful  principle  of  life  is  given,  a  principle  which 
is  regarded  as  the  sum  and  substance  of  the  whole  matter, 
including  within  itself  everything  that  is  necessary  for  its 
own  development.  It  is  held  that  faith  is  not  conditioned  by 
any  external  authority,  since  in  it  Christ  lives  in  us,  and  thus 
from  its  own  inherent  energy  and  power  of  self-development 
it  has  the  right  to  legislate  for  itself.  The  Evangelical  Church, 
on  the  contrary,  rightly  insists  upon  the  tertius  usus  legis. 
Faith  does  not  enable  us  to  dispense  with  Christ  as  an 
objective,  external  law.  For  at  first  it  is  weak,  and  has  to 
grow  up  into  strength,  and  it  can  only  grow  by  means  of  the 
same  power  that  gave  it  birth — that  is,  through  Christ.  Thus 
faith  as  being  imperfect  ever  stands  in  need  of  counsel  and 
instruction,  and  must  direct  itself  according  to  the  standard  of 
the  objective  perfect  law  which  is  given  in  Christ.  Of  course, 
to  take  Christ  as  the  law  of  faith  is  not  a  relapse  under  mere 
outward  authority ;  it  is  the  means  by  which  man  is  brought 
to  repentance,  and  grows  in  knowledge  and  in  freedom. 


SECOND    SECTION. 

CHRIST  THE  ALL-EMBRACING  VIRTUE,  AND  THE  MAN  WHO 
RENDERS  SATISFACTION  TO  GOD. 

§41. 

Christ  is  tJie  Love  of  God  hecome  Man  ;  and  thus  He  is  the 
Virtue  or  Excellence  of  our  race  in  a  personal  form,  and 
the  Man  who  renders  satisfaction  to  God. 

[Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  §  122  (119). — Ed.] 

1.  As  is  shown  in  Dogmatics,  the  appearance  of  Christ  in 
humanity,  in  accordance  with  God's  eternal  purpose  of  recon- 
ciliation, is  sufficient  to  ensure  the  possibility  of  reconciliation  ; 
its  actual  accomplishment,  however,  is  a  work  which  must  be 


CHKIST  THE  SUBSTITUTE  OF  HUMANITY.  349 

carried  out  by  the  God-man  in  an  ethical  way.  If  in  Christ 
only  an  act  of  God  were  to  be  seen,  then  we  should  have  to 
assume  that  God  could  at  once,  and  apart  from  Christ  altogether, 
have  forgiven  all  men  alike,  and  absolved  them  from  guilt 
and  punishment.  In  that  case  nothing  would  be  gained  and 
accomplished  by  the  work  of  the  God-man  which  did  not 
already  exist  in  God.  At  the  most,  Christ  would  only  teach 
and  prove  something,  perhaps  that  God  in  Himself  is  recon- 
ciled with  sin  from  all  eternity,  although  this  would  do  away 
with  the  absolute  reprehensibility  of  wickedness,  and  its 
absolute  liability  to  punishment.  But,  on  the  contrary, — 
while  it  is,  of  course,  true  that  everything  depends  ultimately 
on  the  act  of  God  which  sent  Christ  into  the  world, — the  God- 
man  acquired  a  merit  that  has  moral  value  in  the  eyes  of 
God,  a  merit  which  became  the  salvation  of  humanity,  and 
which,  were  it  not  for  Christ's  work,  would  be  non-existent 
even  for  God.  His  own  personal  virtue,  of  which  love  was  the 
centre,  being  put  to  the  proof  and  tried,  became  a  satisfaction 
with  regard  to  God,  and  thus  He  acquired  a  merit  which 
benefits  the  whole  of  humanity. 

(ft)  First  of  all,  Christ  is  the  23crson  in  whom  humanity 
satisfies  the  universal  law  of  God.  Through  His  own  per- 
sonal virtue  He  has,  as  a  man,  rendered  complete  satisfaction 
to  the  demands  of  the  divine  law,  including  the  law  of  love. 

(&)  But  inasmuch  as  He  is  also  the  man  who  stands  in  an 
essential  relation  to  all  men,  His  love  has  a  unique  function 
to  discharge.  Since  His  sinless  holiness  is  exhibited  amid  a 
race  of  sinners  with  whom  He  is  in  vital  connection.  His 
love  has  assigned  to  it  a  vocation,  a  peculiar  position  and 
duty, — the  duty,  namely,  not  merely  of  recognising  or  judging 
the  sin  and  guilt  of  humanity,  but  of  taking  the  place  of  men 
as  their  high  priest,  and  of  bearing,  in  sympathy  with  them, 
their  burden  of  sin  and  guilt,  in  order  to  wipe  it  away.  And 
to  do  this,  Christ,  in  His  substitutionary  love  and  high-priestly 
sympathy,  had  to  take  upon  Himself  the  sense  of  the  divine 
displeasure  that  hung  over  a  guilt-laden  world :  He  affirmed 
its  justice,  He  tasted  it,  and  would  not  save  mankind  in  any 
way  that  might  lessen  the  gravity  of  guilt,  or  affect  the  justice 
of  that  divine  displeasure  in  which  the  whole  punishment  of 
sin  is  summed  up.     Thus  from  His  personal  purity  and  the 


350  §  41.    CHEIST  THE  ALL-ExMBRACING  YIETUE. 

strength  of  His  love  on  the  one  hand,  and  from  His  unique 
position  to  humanity  on  the  other,  He  had  to  evince  His  love 
in  a  way  that  was  quite  peculiar  and  oflicial.  And  this  He 
did  by  converting  the  suffering  He  endured  from  the  world's 
sin  into  suffering  for  the  world's  sin ;  and  also  by  not  shrink- 
ing from  what  was  the  hardest  thing  of  all,  —  to  bear  in 
sympathy  the  sin  of  the  world,  become  the  substitute  of 
sinful  men,  and  sacrifice  Himself  for  their  sake. 

(c)  His  sacrifice,  moreover,  is  a  merit,  a  sacred  possession 
of  humanity.  For  what  the  God-man  did  and  suffered,  God 
in  His  love  both  can  and  will  make  to  be  a  benefit  for  all 
men,  Not,  indeed,  on  account  of  their  relation  to  Christ,  for 
as  yet  they  do  not  believe  in  Him  and  love  Him,  but  on 
account  of  Christ's  relation  to  them,  or  because  from  love  to 
them  He  has  become  their  substitute.  The  result  of  this 
relationship  of  Christ  to  men  is,  that  henceforth  God  no  longer 
looks  upon  humanity  simply  as  reprehensible  and  failing  in  the 
duty  it  owes  Him.  One  who  belongs  to  it  has,  in  substitu- 
tionary love,  fully  satisfied  the  divine  law ;  and  He  who  has 
done  so  is  not  a  mere  single  atom  of  humanity,  but  One  in 
wliom  the  moral  energy  of  the  whole  race  resides,  and  who  is 
destined  to  be  its  centre  and  head.  In  the  person  of  one  at 
least,  humanity  satisfies  the  love  and  justice  of  God ;  He  has 
made  atonement  to  the  honour  of  divine  justice,  and  rendered 
what  it  demands :  incorporated  with  humanity.  He  is  a 
historical  power  within  it,  and  as  Son  of  man  has  a  lasting 
relation  to  all  men.  Such  a  display  and  proof  of  love  in 
absolute  union  with  justice,  thus  given  in  historical  shape  in 
the  midst  of  humanity,  is  an  ethical  good  of  absolute  worth, 
a  sacred  treasure  laid  up  for  all  mankind,  which,  in  the  eyes 
of  God,  mankind  can  never  lose.  It  is  an  ethical  product 
which  is  itself  productive,  and  continues  to  act  with  creative 
power  throughout  all  generations.  It  is  set  up  in  the  midst 
of  the  ages,  in  order  that  men  by  receiving  it  may  have  the 
moral  principle  implanted  within  them  in  the  fulness  of  its 
power  (Eom,  iii.  25).  For  sanctification  is  the  goal  of  atone- 
ment and  justification. 

The  God-man,  moreover,  also  occupies  an  important  posi- 
tion in  His  state  of  exaltation.  As  intercessor  He  is  tlie 
substitute  for  the   imjperfection  of  believers,  so  that  they   as 


§  42.    CHRIST  THE  KING  OF  THE  KINGDOM  OF  GOD.         ool 

being  united  to  Him,  and  thus  virtually  sanctified,  can  go 
forward  courageously  and  in  the  peace  of  God.  The  historical 
work  likewise,  which  is  carried  on  amongst  unlelievers  for  His 
sake,  continues  to  advance  through  His  power  and  His  inter- 
cession on  their  behalf.  Hence  the  God-man  is  the  noblest, 
the  most  indispensable  good  in  the  ethical  world.  Through 
Him  that  world  is  an  actual  "  mundus,  /cocryu,o9,"  partly  because 
it  already  belongs  to  Him,  so  far  as  it  is  pure  and  well- 
ordered,  partly  because  it  is  destined  to  become  His. 

THIED    SECTION. 

CHRIST  AS  THE  PEINCIPLE  OF  THE  KINGDOM  OF  GOD,  AND  THE 
HEAD  OF  HUMANITY. 

§42. 

The  archetypal  and  substitutionary  or  high-priestly  love  of 
Christ  is  also  invested  v/itli  power  or  efficacy.  Christ 
is  the  King  of  love,  since  He  sends  into  our  hearts  the 
spirit  of  reconciliation  and  love,  and  becomes  the  Founder 
of  a  kingdom  of  God's  children.  These  being  conformed 
to  His  death  and  life  constitute  together  with  Him  a 
Kingdom  or  Whole,  the  Highest  Good  upon  earth.  Thus 
in  Christ  and  His  threefold  office  the  chief  good  begins 
its  existence,  in  a  personal  form,  and  endowed  with  an 
infinite  fulness  of  power.  [Cf.  System  of  Christian 
Doctrine,  iii.  §  110. — Ed.] 

1.  Christ  was  indeed  born  a  king.  He  is  the  Word  made 
flesh  (John  i.  14),  the  reflection  of  the  majesty  of  the  divine 
nature,  and  His  Davidic  descent  symbolizes  His  natural  claim 
to  be  King  of  the  kingdom  of  God  (John  iii.  35,  xviii.  37  ; 
Col.  i.  13-20  ;  Heb.  i.  1-6).  He  ascribes  to  Himself  h^ovala 
over  all  flesh  (Matt.  xi.  27,  xxviii.  18  ff. ;  John  xvii.  2). 
But  the  ethical  character  of  His  person  and  work  is  shown  in 
the  fact  that  He  by  no  means  enters  into  direct  possession  of 
this  kingdom  of  supreme  power,  but  rather,  and  just  as  if  He 
were  not  in  Himself  a  king,  goes  out  to  seek  His  subjects 


352       §  42.    CHRIST  THE  PKINCIPLE  OF  THE  KINGDO.M  OF  GOD. 

and  win  them  to  Himself  by  His  love.  He  and  God  who 
is  in  Him  will  have  nothing  to  do  with  a  kingdom  in  which 
mere  might  and  majesty  are  the  ruling  powers.  God  has 
already  such  a  kingdom  in  nature.  No,  Christ  seeks  to  rule 
in  the  hearts  of  men  by  first  winning  their  hearts  to  Himself. 
That  kingdom  which  is  His  by  right  He  first  builds  up  for 
Himself  by  ministering  love,  in  humiliation,  and  consequently 
by  ethical  means ;  even  as  it  is  also  in  an  ethical  way  that 
He  becomes  that  which  in  Himself  He  is  (§  40.  2).  Nay, 
even  in  His  exaltation  He  withholds  any  display  of  mere 
power, — in  order  to  leave  room  for  freedom  of  choice, — stakes 
everything  upon  believing  faith,  and  waits  until  His  love, 
which  meanwhile  suffers  itself  to  be  misjudged,  shall  lead 
men  to  decide  for  Him  inwardly  and  freely. 

On  the  other  hand,  however,  with  regard  to  the  time  during 
which  His  love  is  a  suppliant,  the  time  when  His  kingly 
dignity  is  veiled  in  the  lowliness  of  His  person  and  king- 
dom,— with  regard  to  this  period  it  is  very  far  from  being  a 
matter  of  indifference  whether  in  Himself  He  possesses  royal 
rank  and  supreme  power  or  not.  For  if  in  Him  there 
were  no  inherent  sovereignty  which  stooped  to  humiliation, 
but  if,  on  the  contrary.  His  dignity  were  entirely  the 
reward  of  His  virtue,  then  the  impression  made  by  His 
condescending  love  would  lack  an  element  of  essential  im- 
portance,— the  contrast,  namely,  between  His  royal  dignity 
and  His  lowly  estate,  which  more  than  anything  else  gives  to 
the  latter  its  wonderfully  captivating  power  (Phil.  ii.  6  ; 
2  Cor.  viii.  9).  The  mind  and  spirit  of  a  king,  the  conscious- 
ness of  i^ovaia,  appears  in  all  that  He  does  and  says  ;  and  it 
is  just  by  reason  of  His  greatness  and  majesty  forming  a  foil 
to  His  love,  that  the  voluntariness  and  grandeur  of  that  love 
are  so  clearly  displayed  ("  Who  for  the  joy  that  was  set  before 
Him  endured  the  cross,"  Heb.  xii.  2). 

Moreover,  what  makes  Him  absolutely  trustworthy  for 
faith  is  that  He  has  shown  Himself  to  be  a  king,  and  is 
thereby  pledged  to  prove  Himself  the  supreme  power  over 
everything  that  exists,  the  founder  and  king  of  the  one  ever- 
lasting kingdom,  from  which  He  will  cast  out  all  that  is 
impure  and  vile  (Eph.  v.  27,  ii.  6,  18-22,  i.  20-23  ;  Matt. 
XXV.    31    f.  ;   1    John  iv.    16    f.  ;  Heb.    xii.    22-28).      And 


I 


CHRIST  THE  PEIXCIPLE  OF  ItEPENTANCE  AND  EIGHTEOUSNESS.   353 

although,  during  the  course  of  the  world's  history,  His  kingly 
majesty,  considered  as  mere  external  power,  is  still  kept  con- 
cealed by  Him  even  as  against  His  foes,  yet  the  time  is 
coming  when  it  will  be  outwardly  revealed.  And  even  now 
His  royal  power  is  operative  in  the  world,  in  an  ethical  form 
namely,  and  therefore  in  a  way  which  enables  man  to  decide 
freely  for  Him,  not  from  prudence  or  fear,  bnt  from  a  longing 
after  divine  good.  His  self-forgetful  love  is  not  without 
effect ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  ever  efficacious.  The  precious 
seed  of  the  life  of  the  God-man  falls  into  the  earth  indeed  and 
dies,  but  only  that  it  may  bring  forth  much  fruit.  The  high- 
priestly  love  of  Christ  proves  itself  the  true  king  of  human 
hearts  ;  for  by  His  devotion  to  and  for  the  sake  of  men  He 
leads  them  to  surrender  themselves  to  Him,  and  binds  them 
to  Himself  so  that  His  spirit  becomes  a  ruling  power  over 
them. 

(«)  The  first  thing  He  does  is  to  give  to  those  who 
receive  Him  His  own  spirit  of  righteousness  and  truth,  the 
spirit  which  led  Him  to  suffer  for  the  sin  of  humanity  as 
well  as  from  it ;  so  that  they  now  abhor  what  is  evil,  and 
recognise,  as  He  did,  the  guilt  and  punishableness  both  of  the 
individual  and  of  the  race  (John  xvi.  8).  The  power  of  His 
suffering  love  becomes  in  them  the  principle  of  repentance, 
and  brings  them  into  the  fellowship  of  His  death  (liom.  vi. 

1  f.),  so  that  they  die  to  themselves,  and  knovir  that  in  Him 
they  are  at  once  judged  and  reconciled. 

{h)  But  Christ  brings  the  old  nature  to  death  through 
repentance,  in  order  that  man  may  be  filled  with  the  spirit 
of  peace  and  sonship,  and  become  a  new  man  (Eom.  viii. 
15).  From  the  first-born  Son  of  God  the  rights  of  children 
are  transmitted  to  us. 

(c)  Moreover,  Christ's  fulfilment  of  the  law  is  also  shadowed 
forth  in  believers  (Rom.  viii.  4—6,  9-14,  vi.  15  f.),  and  there- 
with Christ,  as  our  archetype,  enters  upon  a  new  form  of 
activity.  He  becomes  our  example.  As  archetype  He 
becomes  productive  in  us.  By  our  being  made  partakers 
of  the  TTvevfjia   (John  iv.    14,  vii.  38,  xii.  24,  xvi.  7,   13  f.; 

2  Cor.  V.  17),  our  souls  become  fashioned  after  the  likeness  of 
the  image  of  Christ.  To  SiKaicofxa  tov  vofiov  liK-qpovrai  iv 
i-jfjbiv.      Believers  are  now  no  longer  SouXoi  merely  (Eom.  viii. 


354    §  42.  ClIiaST  THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  THE  KINGDOM  OF  GOD. 

15  ;  John  xv.  15),  with  conscience  and  inclination  still  apart, 
and  with  the  principle  that  rnles  their  wills  outside  of  them 
instead  of  in  them.  For  they  themselves  now  have  the  irvev/xa, 
having  been  apprehended  they  now  themselves  apprehend, 
nay,  they  have  become  the  possessors  of  the  divine  life,  and 
by  them  it  is  wrought  out  in  the  world.  And  therewith  the 
highest  good  also  begins  its  existence  in  the  believer ;  the 
three  fundamental  forms  of  morality  which  are  united  in 
Christ  are  reflected  also  in  him,  and  their  union  begins  and  is 
carried  on  through  the  exercise  of  Christ's  kingly  power. 

(d)  But  now,  while  believers  make  progress  as  single 
individuals,  and  have  their  natural  capacities  purified  and 
animated  by  the  Spirit  of  God,  they  do  not  remain  in  isolation 
from  each  other,  as  a  mere  multiplicity  of  free  citizens  of  the 
kingdom  of  God,  and  forming  a  unity  only  through  their 
relation  to  Christ,  their  common  centre.  On  the  contrary, 
they  are  all  bound  to  each  other  in  a  fellowship  of  love  in 
that  kingdom ;  and  besides,  they  group  themselves  together 
and  form  particular  communities  within  it,  so  that  the  king- 
dom of  God  organizes  itself  in  a  plurality  of  different  spheres, 
which  all  belong  one  to  the  other  as  members  of  the  whole. 

In  what  has  been  said  we  have  brought  to  view  the 
contents  of  the  two  remaining  Divisions,  which  treat  of  the 
World  of  the  Good  in  its  highest  realization.  (1)  The  Individual 
Christian  Personality.  (2)  The  Organized  World  of  Christian 
Morality,  or  the  Christian  Communities.  According  to  the 
evangelical  type  of  doctrine,  we  must  begin  with  the  first  of 
these, — and  for  this  reason,  because  true  Christian  life  cannot 
exist  unless  through  a  death  which  the  individual  dies ;  and 
until  individuals  live  this  Christian  life  they  cannot  be  true 
members  of  a  community,  any  more  than  the  community 
itself  can  take  a  Christian  shape.  The  Eoman  Catholic 
Church,  on  the  contrary,  begins  with  the  Church  as  an  institu- 
tion for  the  salvation  of  men.  It  does  not  permit  the 
individual  to  come  into  connection  with  Christ  directly,  but 
only  through  the  Church,  the  representative  of  Christ.  By 
this  means  the  freedom  and  equality  of  believing  members 
are  sacrificed  to  dependence  upon  the  ecclesiastical  institution 
and  the  clergy.  Moreover,  since  the  religious  community  has 
a  sort  of  divine  position  assigned  it,  in  which   it  is  held  to 


CHRIST  AND  THE  CHURCH.  355 

control  the  operations  of  the  Holy  Spirit,  it  is  set  in  a  false 
relation  to  other  moral  communities,  and  these  are  lowered  out 
of  their  rightful  place. 

It  is  true  that  according  to  the  Evangelical  Church  also 
preaching  or  word  and  sacrament  must  precede  faith  (Eom. 
X.  17);  but  these  are  not  the  Church,  they  are  simply  the 
continuation  of  the  activity  of  Christ.  Thus  the  Evangelical 
doctrine  avoids  two  opposite  errors — the  spiritualistic  and  the 
empirical  ^  (Roman  Catholic)- — by  teaching,  on  the  one  hand, 
that  there  is  no  Church  until  there  are  i't'7'c  creclentes,  that  it  is 
socictas  field  et  Spiritits  Sancti  (Conf.  Aug.  vii.  viii.)  ;  and,  on  the 
other,  that  faith  can  only  be  attained  by  means  of  word  and 
sacrament.  These  are  vehicles  by  which  we  arrive  at  imme- 
diate fellowship  with  Christ.  They  are  the  bridge,  way,  or 
path  to  Him,  by  means  of  which,  even  now,  Christ  Himself 
in  the  Holy  Spirit  keeps  up  intercourse  with  men.  But 
Christ  has  by  no  means  appointed  the  Church  to  be  the  sub- 
stitu.te  for  His  personal  activity  and  His  mission  of  the  Spirit ; 
it  is  only  the  organ  tlirough  which  He  carries  out  His  purpose 
that  salvation  be  preached  and  offered  to  men.  [Cf.  System  of 
Christian  Doctrine,  i\.  §  128. — Ed.] 


SECOND    DIVISION. 

CHRISTIAN  VIRTUE  AS  EXHIBITED  IN  THE  INDIVIDUAL. 

§  43.  Introduction. 

The  principle  of  moral  perfection  which  is  in  Christ  is  designed 
to  be  transmitted  to  us  by  our  being  receptive  towards 
the  love  of  the  God-man,  or  towards  the  communication 
of  His  redeeming  and  perfecting  power.  This  receiving 
of  Christ  is  faith.  Faith  is  the  fundamental  excellence 
or  virtue  (of  a  receptive  nature)  exhibited  by  the 
redeemed,  because  it  is   the  willingness  to  receive   the 

^  Empirical,  because  tlie  Roman  Catholic  Cliurcli  stops  short  with  tlie  empi- 
rical Cliurch  as  the  goal,  instead  of  rising  to  Christ  in  faith. 


356  §  43.   CHRISTIAN  VIIiTUE  IN  THE  INDIVIDUAL. 

love  of  Christ  in  its  reconciling,  sanctifying,  and  per- 
fecting power.  Moreover,  since  faith  gives  its  assent  to 
Christ  and  His  saving  purpose,  and  allows  itself  to  be 
determined,  yea,  filled  by  His  power  as  liedeemer,  it 
becomes  an  image  of  that  union  of  law,  virtue,  and  the 
chief  good  whicli  is  exhibited  in  Christ.  That  is  to  say, 
in  faith  the  perfect  Good  beghis  to  be  realized  in  a  new, 
spontaneous,  and  productive  life.  Of  its  own  free  M'ill 
faith  makes  what  it  has  received  its  own,  and  thus  a 
new,  spontaneous,  and  productive  life  is  created.  This 
new  life  reveals  itself  both  as  knowledge  and  as  will. 
When  it  takes  the  character  of  knoivlcdf/e  of  the  highest 
ideal  aim,  there  arises  tlie  virtue  of  Christian  hope 
(or  wisdom)  ;  when  it  takes  the  character  of  vjill,  we 
have  the  virtue  of  Christian  love,  which  is  the  fulfilling 
of  the  law. 

1.  Christ  at  first  stands  over  against  us  objectively,  as  the 
law  of  faith  and  life,  and  demands  that  we  put  faith  in  His 
act  of  atonement  and  in  His  purpose  to  perfect  us,  while  He 
also  demands  that  we  imitate  His  life.  But  He  also  initiates 
the  fulfilment  of  this  law  by  taking  us  into  fellowship  witli 
Himself.  He  conveys  His  image  and  His  Spirit  out  of  their 
bare  objectivity  into  our  inmost  nature,  and  makes  them  our 
own  possession.  And  when  this  has  been  done,  man  has  now 
the  law  of  his  life  and  spirit  within  himself  (Eom.  viii.  1  ff.). 

This,  then,  is  the  subject  which  our  Second  Division  has  to 
take  up,  viz.  the  Christian  in  Ids  individual  personality.  That 
Division  must  contain  the  doctrine  of  the  moral  excellence  or 
virtue  which  is  produced  when  the  moral  law  has  obtained  an 
entrance  into  man's  heart,  and  has  thus  reached  that  personal 
mode  of  existence  which  it  is  meant  to  have.  It  must  there- 
fore treat  of  Ethical  Dynamics,  or  the  doctrine  of  Moral  Energy. 
And  this  it  must  do  in  such  a  way  as  at  the  same  time  to  bring 
to  light  the  operations  or  functions  of  this  energy  ;  that  is,  those 
acts  of  virtue  {or  of  duty)  hy  means  of  icliich  moved  excellences  and 
moral  communities  are  originated  or  maintained.  For  as  soon 
as  the  individual  has  become  a  Christian,  there  lies  immanent 


FAITH  THE  FUNDAMENTAL  CHRISTIAN  VIETUE.  357 

within  him,  as  an  end  and  impulse,  the  activity  which  has  to 
he  manifested  in  the  kingdom  of  God.  He  cannot  remain 
idle,  or  enjoy  a  dream-life  of  mere  egoism.  For  he  has  been 
set  down  in  the  midst  of  a  Whole,  in  the  world,  namely,  which 
has  to  be  moulded  into  moral  shape,  and  made  the  kingdom 
of  God ;  and  of  this  kingdom,  which  is  the  highest  good, 
the  Christian  himself  is  already  a  part,  and  that  a  productive 
one.  The  compassion  of  Christ  for  the  sin  and  misery  of  the 
world  is  reflected  in  believers  also,  and  arouses  their  readiness 
to  work  and  suffer  for  His  sake,  for  His  kingdom,  and  His 
glory  (Col.  i.  24). 

In  the  Christian  personality  itself  there  is  a  multiplicity  of 
energies,  but  these  are  all  combined  in  it  so  as  to  form  a  unity, 
in  which  the  divine  life  and  the  human  have  entered  into 
union  with  each  other.  At  first,  Christ  is  the  whole  virtuous 
energy  of  our  race ;  but  this  is  not  yet  07u^  virtue.  Nay,  His 
virtue  cannot,  and  is  not  to  become  ours  so  as  to  leave  no 
distinction  between  them.  He  is  the  God-man,  we  are  to 
become  men  of  God.  His  virtue  is  that  of  the  Head  of 
humanity — prevenient,  redeeming,  communicating  love  ;  we 
who  are  to  be  redeemed  stand  to  Him  in  the  position  of 
recipients,  or  as  those  who  ^int  faith  in  His  creative,  because 
God-incarnate  love.  Hence,  while  our  virtue  must  indeed 
correspond  with  the  Redeemer's,  this  does  not  mean  that  it  is 
to  be  a  repetition  of  His  redeeming  love,  but  that  through  a 
believing  experience  of  His  love  we  from  being  the  recipients 
of  it  are  to  become  loving  ourselves. 

Further,  in  order  that  we  may  resemble  Christ  in  all  His 
perfection,  all  our  powers  must  enter  as  recipients  into  the 
act  of  faith,  and  Christ  must  also  be  received  in  His  entirety. 
Intelligence,  will,  and  feeling  are  alike  appealed  to  by  Christ, 
until  through  His  image  and  the  working  of  His  Spirit  all 
these  functions  are  brouG;ht  to  converge  into  one  focus,  into  the 
living  receptivity  of  the  whole  nature,  and  there  the  spark  of 
life  can  now  fall,  and  the  new  God-created  personality  arise. 
This  receiving  of  Christ  is  not  mere  helpless  passivity ;  it 
involves  self-determination,  a  willingness  to  be  determined  by 
the  Eedeemer ;  and  for  this  reason  faith  is  treated,  both  in 
Scripture  and  in  Church  confessions,  as  a  virtue  (1  Cor. 
xiii.  13). 


358  §  43.  CHRISTIAN  VIUTUE  IN  THE  INDIVIDUAL. 

Since  faith  thus  marks  the  fundamental  position  which  the 
Christian  holds,  or  is  the  fundamental  Christian  virtue,  it 
contains  in  embryo  the  Christian  character  in  general.  Hope 
and  love,  however,  as  we  shall  shortly  see,  are  the  essential 
forms  in  which  it  manifests  its  life ;  they  come  into  existence 
along  with  faith,  and  with  it  constitute  the  new  man.  In 
faith  man  attains  to  a  good  state  of  being,  of  objective  worth 
while  subjective  in  form,  and  out  of  this  goodness  of  the  new 
man  there  now  arise  single  virtues  and  virtuous  acts.  Faith 
in  the  Christian  is  the  copy  of  what  Christ  was  as  the  God- 
man  ;  what  He  became  through  the  act  of  incarnation  we 
become,  representatively,  when  we  receive  His  redeeming 
power.  Through  faith  we  become  children  of  God,  as  Christ 
is  the  Son  of  God.  As  firm,  unbroken  union  with  God  in 
Christ,  as  trust  and  confidence  in  Him,  and  also  as  simple 
receptiveness,  faith  never  ceases ;  as  imperfect  knowledge, 
however,  it  is  destined  to  come  to  an  end  in  perfect  know- 
ledge, that  is,  in  sight.  In  1  Cor.  xiii.  13,  love  is  said  to  be 
greater  than  faith,  just  as  the  ripe  fruit  is  better  than  its 
sreen  beginning ;  nevertheless  the  beginning  lives  on  in  the 
growth. 

But  now  the  question  arises — if  faitli  is  thus  the  unity, 
in  principle,  of  all  Christian  excellence,  how  are  we  to  arrive 
at  the  manifold  variety  of  Christian  virtues  ?  and  more,  how 
can  we,  in  order  to  preserve  the  unity,  evolve  the  diversity 
from  it  ? 

2.  Analysis  and  Classification  of  the  Forms  of  Virtue. — In 
the  ancient  world,  ethics  oscillates — to  use  the  language  of 
Schleiermacher — between  two  extremes.  On  the  one  hand, 
virtue  is  regarded  as  a  unity  which  refuses  to  admit'of  analysis 
or  separation  into  component  parts  (as  in  Stoicism) ;  while,  on 
the  other,  we  are  presented  with  a  multiplicity  of  virtues, 
and  still  more  of  virtuous  acts,  which  are  taken  up  em- 
pirically merely,  and  are  not  brought  together  into  unity. 
AiKaioavvri  is  almost  regarded  as  the  highest  good,  but  is 
too  formal  to  admit  of  all  the  virtues  being  derived  from  it. 
Rothe  takes,  as  the  basis  of  his  analysis  of  the  forms  of  virtue, 
a  consideration  of  the  objective  work,  the  moral  good  for 
which  they  exist ;  and  defines  virtue  as  that  peculiar  property 
of  the  individual  man,  which  makes  him  specifically  fitted  for 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  FORMS  OF  VIRTUE.  359 

the  realization  of  the  highest  good.  But  virtue  does  not 
exist  merely  for  the  sake  of  something  else  than  itself ;  in 
itself  it  is  also  an  ultimate  end  and  a  good.  Objective  works 
too,  if  they  are  to  be  produced  by  human  beings,  must  pre- 
suppose that  there  is  already  in  these  beings  something  corre- 
sponding with  themselves.  So  we  confine  ourselves,  to  begin 
with,  to  the  person  of  the  believer,  in  whom  the  virtuous 
power  resides,  and  inquire  here  after  a  basis  for  our  classifica- 
tion. 

Now  we  have  seen  that  in  the  human  personality — (1) 
distinctions  of  a  mental  kind  are  to  be  found  ;  especially  that 
between  knowing  and  willing.  The  latter  faculties,  when 
occupied  with  what  is  moral,  appear  as  conscience  and 
freedom  (§  11,  12).  (2)  Further,  we  have  in  man  the 
distinction  between  mind  and  nature.  We  have  now  to 
relate  faith — this  unity,  this  fundamental  receptive  virtue — 
to  both  of  these  antitheses,  in  order  to  watch  its  development, 
and  so  obtain  the  classification  which  we  seek. 

(a)  A  basis  for  the  classification  of  the  forms  of  virtue  is 
given  us,  first  of  all,  from  the  mental  side  of  the  moral  con- 
stitution, in  the  distinction  between  conscience  and  freedom  ; 
and  this  distinction  refers  ns  back  to  that  between  knowing 
and  willing,  the  union  of  which  is,  as  we  have  seen,  the  moral 
task  which  has  to  be  accomplished.  Now,  if  faith  be  really 
the  fundamental  virtue,  we  must  be  able  to  show  that  in  it 
there  is  the  unity  of  conscience  and  freedom,  that  in  it  the 
process  has  actually  begun  by  which  these  are  to  be  truly 
interwoven  with  each  other.  In  faith,  conscience  is  sharpened 
and  on  the  alert,  caprice  or  false  freedom  is  negated  througli 
repentance,  and  the  will  is  turned  towards  the  good,  the 
etliically  free  towards  the  ethically  necessary.  Accordingly, 
there  is  in  faith,  in  fact,  the  double  germ  of  two  moral  forces 
or  virtues  which  are  held  by  it  in  nnity,  the  one  referring  to 
cognition  and  conscience,  the  other  to  the  will.  But  these  do 
not  lose  their  distinction  in  faith.  Moral  progress  is  possible 
only  through  the  fact  that  while  the  bond  which  unites  them, 
viz.  faith,  remains  unsundered,  it  is  at  one  time  the  cog- 
nitive element,  at  another  the  volitional,  which  becomes 
predominant. 

Now  the   new  man,  as  free   and  exercising  will,  possesses 


360  §  43.  CHRISTIAN  VIRTUE  IX  THE  INDIVIDUAL. 

Christian  love ;  as  exercising  cognition,  he  possesses  Christian 
vnsdom.  If  faith  is  the  fundamental  receptive  virtue  of  the 
Christian,  wisdom  and  love  together  form  his  fundamental 
productive  virtue.  Both  of  these  determine  each  other 
reciprocally  and  act  together,  but  each  has  its  special 
function.  Wisdom  constructs  the  aims  of  ethical  production 
— wisdom,  of  course,  enriched  by  the  spirit  of  love.  Love, 
again,  is  the  basis  of  the  Christian  disposition,  it  gives  the 
will  its  virtuous  character.  Hence  Scripture  sees  in  love,  as 
the  inward  disposition  of  the  believer,  the  unity  of  all  free 
moral  excellence,  the  fulfilling  and  "  avaKe(^aKaio3cn^  "  of  the 
whole  law  (Eom.  xiii.  8  f.  ;  Matt.  xxii.  40).  But,  on  the 
other  hand,  in  order  that  love  may  find  active  exercise,  it  is 
necessary  that  ideals  be  properly  formed,  and  that  tlie  right 
means  be  found  whereby  they  are  to  be  realized.  Hence  love 
itself  gives  to  cognition  the  impulse  to  become  wisdom — 
wisdom  based  upon  that  knowledge,  given  in  faith,  which  is 
its  foundation  and  beginning,  the  knowledge  of  God  in  Clirist. 
Thus  Christian  wisdom  and  love  spring  simultaneously  from 
faith,  as  co-ordinate  virtues  which  have  their  unity  in  true 
faith.  Of  course,  the  concrete  exercise  of  love  presupposes 
the  exercise  of  wisdom,  for  what  is  willed  from  motives  of 
love  must  have  previously  existed  in  thought  and  been 
recognised  to  be  a  good.  Still,  love,  as  the  Christian  dis- 
position, must  co-operate  in  the  formation  of  ideals. 

But  now,  how  does  what  we  have  said  agree  with  the  fact 
that  in  1  Cor.  xiii.  13  it  is  hope  that  is  mentioned  in  the 
place  of  Christian  wisdom,  and  that  our  thesis  treats  hope  as 
tlie  intellectual  virtue  which  springs  from  faith  ?  Is  not  hope 
a  much  narrower  concept  than  wisdom  ?  Knowledge  certainly 
embraces  a  wider  field  than  hope.  Hope  directs  its  gaze  to 
the  future,  while  faith,  as  distinct  from  it,  has  regard  to  acts 
of  God  in  the  past,  and  love  lives  chiefly  in  the  irrescnt.  But 
if  we  leave  out  of  sight  the  knowledge  of  past  acts  of  God, 
since  faith  already  possesses  such  a  knowledge,  then  Christian 
wisdom  is  directed,  before  everything  else,  to  the  true  xeXo?, 
to  the  good  things  that  are  imperishable.  And  more  than  this, 
it  is  not  a  barren  knowledge,  like  so  much  that  does  not  deserve 
the  name  ;  it  is  a  knowledge  that  wills  the  highest  ends,  and 
carries  in  itself  the  certainty  of  their  accomplishment.      But 


CHRISTIAN  WISDOM  AND  CHRISTIAN  HOPE.  361 

practical  wisdom  such  as  this  is  nothing  else  than  hope, 
which,  inspired  with  faith,  makes  the  future  live  in  the 
present,  apprehends  the  true  goal  to  which  the  world  is  surely 
advancing,  and  holds  it  up  before  love,  that  love  may  take  it 
as  its  own  ^oal  and  work  for  its  attainment.  No  knowledge 
can  be  ethically  fruitful  unless  it  be  of  a  ideological  kind  ;  it 
must  terminate  in  an  end  that  has  to  be  realized,  and  this  end 
forms  the  contents  of  Aopt'.  Thus  we  may,  in  the  strictest 
sense,  take  Christian  hope  and  moral  wisdom  together.  For 
the  latter  is  wisdom  animated  with  a  practical  purpose, 
wisdom  directed  to  the  solution  of  a  moral  problem,  and  all 
other  knowledge  is  of  moral  value  only  as  a  preliminary  con- 
dition of  this  practical  wisdom,  and  as  the  means  which  it 
employs.  It  is  the  crown  of  knowledge  ;  it  is  Christian  hope 
consciously  exercised,  and  apprehending  that  which  is  eternally 
true  and  which  will  yet  be  realized. 

In  another  and  formal  aspect  the  idea  of  hope  is  wider 
than  that  of  moral  wisdom  ;  for  hope  also  includes  courageous 
trust,  assured  confidence  that  the  good  work  will  be  perfected. 
But  it  derives  such  confidence  from  the  knowledge  that  this 
work  has  already  been  begun  (Phil.  i.  4,  6) — that  is  to  say, 
from  faith.  Hence,  in  hope  faith  still  lives  and  acts ;  or,  to 
look  at  the  same  thing  in  another  way,  hope,  in  order  to 
animate  its  courage,  goes  back  to  faith,  which  is  its  root,  just 
as  love  also  derives  its  joy  from  the  same  source.  Thus  when 
we  survey  the  triad  of  faith,  hope,  and  love,  it  is  evident  that 
as  hope  and  love  proceed  from  faith  as  their  source,  so  they 
return  into  it  again  ;  and  consequently  this  triad  forms  the 
complete  whole  of  personal  Christian  morality,- — a  whole  that 
is  even  separating  into  its  component  elements,  and  ever 
returning  to  unity  again. 

(^)  Thus  we  have  the  primary  division  of  Christian  virtue 
into  the  triad  "  faith,  love,  and  wisdom."  A  second  principle 
of  division  is  now  given  us  in  the  further  antithesis  that 
exists  in  the  moral  constitution  between  natvre  and  sinrit — 
spirit,  that  is,  as  the  vov<i  united  with  the  vveu/xa.  Nature  has 
a  relatively  independent  existence.  Hence  it  can  limit  the 
Christian  spirit,  and  it  does  so  through  the  flesh.  Thus  it  is 
the  task  of  the  spirit  to  maintain  itself  against  such  restraints, 
and  not  only  so,  but  also  continually  to  extend  its  dominion. 


3G2  §  43.  CHRISTIAN  VIRTUE  IN  THE  INDIVIDUAL. 

And  this  it  is  possible  for  it  to  do,  because  everything  it 
does  reacts  npon  its  state  or  character  (§  11,  7).  Now  by 
the  practice  of  such  self-assertion,  Christian  virtue  becomes 
hoMt  or  a  second  nature.  Thus  we  arrive  at  the  distinction 
between  virtue  as  an  inward  disposition  and  virtue  as  a  habit 
or  settled  tendency  to  manifest  and  assert  itself.  If  we  now 
apply  what  has  been  said  regarding  virtue  as  a  habit,  or  virtue 
persevered  in  (viroixovrj),  to  the  triad  of  faith,  wisdom,  and  love, 
there  results  (1)  perseverance  in  faith,  which  is  fidelity ;  (2) 
j)erseverance  in  wisdom,  or  sober  -  mindedncss ;  (3)  virtuous 
stedfastness,  or  the  vTro/xovr]  of  love.  The  principle  of  Chris- 
tian virtue  manifests  itself  in  the  second  triad  no  less  than  in 
the  first.  For  it  is  a  living  power  ;  if  it  is  through  the  first 
triad  that  the  Christian  personality,  as  such,  comes  into  Icing, 
it  is  through  the  second  that  it  continues  to  suhsisf. 

Christian  virtue,  moreover,  can  only  assert  itself,  in  spite  of 
the  checks  and  interruptions  which  it  receives,  by  the  faculties 
which  worked  abnormally  and  in  the  service  of  sin  being  more 
and  more  withdrawn  from  the  sway  of  the  sinful  principle, 
and  by  their  being  appropriated  by  and  assimilated  to  the 
renewed  will.  Christianity  does  not  oppose  evil  desires  with 
mere  cold  reason,  in  order  to  control  and  restrain  them.  For  in 
that  case  they  would  always  continue  to  exist  inwardly.  (And 
hence,  if  a  man  were  merely  to  restrain  himself  from  outward 
acts  of  sin,  there  would  still  be  a  contradiction  between  what 
is  inward  and  what  is  outward  ;  the  apparent  good  would  be 
unreal — what  Luther  was  accustomed  to  call  "pharisaic 
holiness.")  Xo,  Christianity  drives  out  evil  desires  by  the 
power  of  a  noUer  one,  by  a  higher  passion  or  entlmsiasm^  so 
that  the  lower  appetites  gradually  wear  out  and  disappear  of 
themselves.  The  more  this  takes  place,  the  more  completely 
does  the  principle  of  virtue  take  possession  of  the  whole  person 
and  faculties  of  man,  and  the  more  thoroughly  does  the  nevj 
personcdity  and  its  moral  excellence  {i.e.  its  virtue  as  a  whole) 
develop  into  a  nevj  manifoldncss  of  virtues  and  virtuous  acts. 
And  further,  the  believer  will,  on  cdl  occasions,  devote  Ms 
virtuous  energies  and  efforts  to  that  portion  of  the  chief  good,  or 
kingdom  of  God,  lohich  ought  to  he  realized, — and  this  hoth  as 
regards  his  individual  character  and  the  outside  luorld. 
1  Cf.  Ecce  Homo,  4th  ed.  1866. 


§  43re.    SYLLABUS. 


363 


Accordingly,  we  have  the  following  division  : — 
§  43a.  Syllaljus. 

FiEST  Section.        The  Genesis  of  the  Christian  Character,  or 

of  the  New  Personality  regarded  as  an 

inward  Suva/jH';. 
Second  Section.     The  Sulsistencc  of  the  Christian  Character 

by  means  of  Virtuous  Self-preservation 

(Ascetics). 
Third  Section.       The  Manifestation  and  Self-development  of 

the  Christian  Character. 


FIEST    SECTION. 


THE  GENESIS  OF  THE  CHRISTIAN  CHARACTER. 


Chapter  Second. 


Chapter  Third. 


Chapter  First.      Of  regenerating  faith,  the  cardinal  receptive 

virtue. 
Of   love,  the  cardinal   productive  virtue    of 

the  loill. 
Of  ivisdom  (Jiop)e),  which,  active  and  inventive 

in  its  own  nature,  becomes,  when  united 

with  love,  the  cardinal  producticc  virtue 

of  the  intellect. 

Note  1. — The  l)lending  together  of  willing  and  knowing,  of 
outward  self-manifestation  and  inward  self-culture. 

Note  2. — Eelation  of  the  four  cardinal  virtues  of  the  ancient 
world,  avdpiia,  diKaiodxjvri,  Gojpposvvri,  (ppo'r/jaig,  to  the  three  Christian 
ones  of  faith,  love,  wisdom  (hope).  By  Schleiermacher  dixaioavvr, 
is  raised  to  the  level  of  love,  while  faith  is  related  to  wisdom 
(ffwppoff'jr/)  and  <pp6v'/i6ig),  so  that  liope  is  left  to  represent  rhdpsiu. 
But  faith  is  not  identical  with  knowledge  ;  it  is  the  principle  of 
love  just  as  well.  Faith  is  rather  the  principle  of  virtue  as  a 
whole,  the  primary  form  in  which  all  virtue  exists,  the  principle 
of  love  as  well  as  of  wisdom.  Inasmuch  as  diy.aiosvvTj  was  very 
commonly  regarded  by  the  ancients  as  embracing  the  whole  of 
virtue,  its  place  is  most  properly  taken  by  faith,  the  true 
foundation  of  the  Christian  character ;  while  iyy-pa-zna  and 
ayhpiia,  as  belonging  to  the  will,  correspond  with  love ;  cu^ppoauvr, 
and  <pp6y/i()ig  (knowledge),  on  the  other  hand,  being  included  in 
hope. 


3G4  §  w.  FAiTir. 

CHAPTER    FIRST. 

FAITH. 

§  44. 

[Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  vol.  i.  pp.  31-184,  especially 
§  11 ;  vol.  iv.  §  128  and  §  131,  132.  Also,  Gcsammclte  Ahhancl- 
lungen  {Ber  Kicler  Vortrag  iiber  Rechtfertlgung,  1867.  Das 
Prinzip  unserer  Kirche),  pp.  48,  153. — Ed.] 

When  the  gospel  of  Christ  is  received  by  the  conscience, 
repentance  is  produced.  The  course  of  repentance,  when 
it  is  pure  and  normal,  is  as  follows.  On  the  one  hand, 
sin  and  guilt  are  seen  in  the  light  of  the  righteousness  of 
Christ,  and  hence  the  knowledge  of  sin  arises ;  on  the 
other,  there  is  an  awakening  of  the  will  to  resist  evil 
and  the  power  of  evil ;  and  these  are  so  united  in  a 
sense  of  remorse  and  pain  that  a  feeling  of  personal 
helplessness  ensues,  or — what  is  the  same  thing  looked 
at  from  another  side — a  feeling  that  higher  help  is  ab- 
solutely needed,  and  a  longing  that  it  may  be  bestowed. 
And  now,  starting  with  this  longing,  a  sceond  loroccss 
commences,  in  which  the  activity  of  the  will  is 
predominant.  The  gospel,  which  initiated  the  process 
of  true  repentance,  now  becomes  a  law  of  faith,  a 
command  addressed  to  man  to  submit  to  be  redeemed 
by  Jesus.  By  this  means  the  conscience  is  enlightened 
to  perceive  that  faith  in  Christ  is  a  moral  duty,  and  the 
human  will,  by  yielding  itself  to  be  apprehended  by 
Christ,  responds  to  His  will  which  seeks  to  apprehend  it. 
Thus  we  arrive  at  that  act  of  faith  which  has  at  once  a 
divine  and  a  human  side,  that  act  in  which  man  rises 
clear  of  the  thought  of  his  own  righteousness  and  merit, 
as  well  as  of  his  own  guilt  and  sin,  and  not  only  sinks 
and  forgets  everything  of  his  own  in  believing  con- 
templation of  Christ,  but  also  gives  his  willing  consent 
to  the  substitution  which  Christ  in  His  love  has  made 


CO-OPEHATION  OF  DIVINE  AND  HUMAN  ACTIVITY.  obo 

for  US.  Thus,  in  the  third  'place,  Christ  can  now  dwell  in 
the  heart  and  give  it  peace ;  He  now  unbosoms  Himself 
to  the  soul  that  has  put  its  trust  in  Him,  and  unites 
Himself  to  it  in  the  bonds  of  love,  that  it  may  realize 
that  the  sin  and  guilt  which  belong  to  it  have  become 
His,  and  are  swallowed  up  in  Him,  while  all  that 
belongs  to  Him  is  now  its  own  possession.  The  blessed 
sense  of  all  this  is  the  light  of  life  to  the  new  man  ;  at 
one  and  the  same  time  he  knows  Christ  as  his  Eedeemer, 
and  himself  as  redeemed  and  a  child  of  God  ;  it  is  a 
human  knowledge,  but  filled  with  divine  certainty. 

[Literature.  —  Kostlin,  Bcr  Glaule.  Jonathan  Edwards, 
ItnnarJiS  on  the  Trinity  and  tlie  Economy  of  Scdvafion,  New 
York  1880,  pp.  64-71.  Gloag,  A  Treatise  on  Justification  by 
Faith,  1856.  Frank,  Systern  der  christlichen  Gewissheit.  System 
der  christlichen  Sittlichkeit,  i.  §  4, 16, 17.  llitschl,  Bechffertif/iiw/, 
etc.,  iii.  cap.  9.  Martensen,  Christian  Ethics,  ii.  p.  142  S(]. 
Itothe,  Theol.  Ethik,  1st  ed.  vol.  ii.  p.  434  sq.— Ed.] 

Note. — In  order  to  understand  how  faith  or  regeneration 
arises,  three  points  will  have  to  be  attended  to.  {a)  At  every 
stage  there  must  be  a  co-operation  of  divine  and  human  activity 
(Ij)  This  activity  must  l)e  exerted  in  two  leading  directions — on 
the  one  hand,  in  repudiating  the  old  life;  on  the  other,  in  turn- 
ing to  the  new  life  of  salvation  in  Christ,  (c)  As  the  entire 
power  of  Christ  was  required  for  our  redemption,  and  was 
manifested  in  the  threefold  oflice  in  which  He  personally 
revealed  Himself,  so  the  activity  which  is  displayed  from  the 
side  of  man,  and  which  is,  as  it  were,  capable  of  admitting  the 
redeeming  power  of  Christ,  demands  the  exercise  of  the  entire 
energy  of  his  nature — chiefly  in  the  way  of  receiving.  And 
this  whole  energy  of  man  is  manifested  both  in  rejecting  what 
is  opposed  to  God  and  in  welcoming  what  is  good,  until  at  last 
it  becomes  indissolubly  united  with  the  moral  power  of  Christ, 
and  his  will  too,  as  recipient,  becomes  one  with  the  will  of 
Christ  as  communicative. 

1.  Tlce  necessity  both  of  the  divine  and  the  human  side  in  the 
ivorh  of  sahation  is  apparent  enough  in  general.  The  whole 
work  of  conversion  is  at  one  and  the  same  time  divine  and 
human.  This  fundamental  principle  is  opposed  both  to  the 
Pelagian  and  the  Magical  theory.      The  Pelagian  is  irreligious, 


366  §  44.  FAITH.       CHKIST  ITS  OBJECT. 

tlie  Magical  is  unethical.  But  true  religion  is  etliical,  and 
rests  on  an  ethical  conception  of  God,  while  true  morality 
does  not  remain  satisfied  with  mere  human  goodness  by  itself. 
Thus  the  Magical  theory  is  only  seemingly  and  superficially 
religious,  the  Pelagian  only  superficially  ethical. 

Now,  if  we  ask  more  definitely  wherein  consists  the  divine 
element  in  the  work  of  regeneration,  and  wherein  the  human, 
tlie  first  point  (as  belonging  to  Dogmatics)  need  not  detain  us. 
The  divine  factor,  to  which  man  must  surrender  himself,  is — 
speaking  generally — Christ,  as  we  have  shown  in  our  First 
Division.  There  we  saw  that  Christ  is  the  Eedeemer  who 
unceasingly  offers  Himself  to  humanity, — primarily  in  Word 
and  Sacrament,  secondarily  in  the  Christian  community, — and 
who  through  His  Spirit  creates  and  establishes  a  new  persoiui,! 
life  in  those  who  accept  Him  in  the  obedience  of  faith.  The 
image  of  Christ  must  be  present  and  efficacious  in  each  stage 
of  the  saving  process,  it  must  accompany  and  direct  them  all. 
Christ  must  be  present  as  the  living  law  of  faith  and  life,  a 
law  which  addresses  itself  to  our  conscience,  but  still  is  more 
than  our  conscience  (1  John  iii.  19  f.),  since  He  prepares  us  to 
receive  Himself  or  to  have  faith  in  Him.  It  is  therefore  by 
no  means  necessary  that  repentance  and  contrition  should 
first  of  all  be  wrought  entirely  by  a  law  apart  from  Christ 
altogether,  and  then,  when  the  penitent  is  in  despair,  that 
something  should  be  communicated  to  him  by  Christ ;  on  the 
contrary,  Christ  may,  nay,  means  to  work  from  the  beginning 
upon  the  hearts  of  children  baptized  into  the  Christian 
Church.  It  would  stamp  the  position  of  Christ  as  merely 
accidental,  and  undertaken  on  account  of  sin,  if  an  extra- 
Christian  legal  economy  had  first  of  all  to  be  brought  into 
operation, — the  remnant,  so  to  speak,  of  an  order  of  the  world 
which  did  not  include  Christ  in  its  original  purpose  at  all. 
He  who  is  the  perfect  law  is  able  of  Himself  to  act  as  law,  to 
bring  men,  on  the  one  side,  to  a  knowledge  of  their  sin  and 
guilt,  and,  on  the  other,  to  penitence  and  heartfelt  shame. 

Outside  of  Christianity  the  knowledge  of  sin  and  guilt  is 
not  so  easily  brought  into  unity  with  penitence.  There  we 
find  only  an  alternation  of  moods ;  at  one  time  man  in  his  con- 
trition rejects  what  is  evil  as  if  sin  had  no  power  within  him,  at 
another  he  knows  he  is  under  the  bondage  of  sin,  but  now  the 


FAITH  OX  ITS  HUMAN  SIDE.  367 

undaunted  resolution  to  reject  sin  in  spite  of  everything  is 
absent  or  extinguished.  The  objective  word  of  Christ,  on 
the  contrary,  has  the  power  of  uniting  these  two  things — on 
the  one  hand,  a  recognition  of  the  depth  of  sin  and  of  the 
bondage  into  which  it  has  brought  us,  and  on  the  other  an  ever- 
hopeful  struggle  against  the  feeling  of  despair  (a  feeling  which 
is  very  apt  to  become  disguised  Pelagianism,  either  resting 
satisfied  with  mere  self-condemnation,  or  finding  refuge  in 
lowering  the  demands  of  the  divine  law  and  minimizing  its 
gravity).  For  the  gospel  of  Christ  holds  out  help  to  every 
one,  and  prevents  despondency,  without,  however,  encouraging- 
recklessness  or  carelessness.  The  image  of  Christ  in  His 
sufferings  for  us  vanquishes  pride,  humbles  us,  and  makes  us 
sensible  of  our  worthlessness  and  of  the  punitive  justice  of 
God,  while  it  nevertheless  restrains  us  from  that  slavish  fear 
which  would  kill  love  at  the  outset.  For  Christ  is  with  us 
and  for  us. 

Note. — When  the  knowledge  of  Christ,  of  His  holiness  and 
grace,  enters  into  the  first  conscious  beginnings  of  life,  the  pro- 
cess of  conversion  runs  its  most  normal  course.  The  accusation 
and  judgment  of  the  law  do  not  then  operate  without  any  sense 
of  grace  accompanying  them,  but  the  state  of  grace  entered 
upon  at  baptism  can  continue  to  last  and  be  carried  forward  to 
perfection.  But  notwithstanding,  the  process  must  take  place. 
This  remains  certain — that  the  old  man  must  be  put  to  deatli 
through  the  will  of  the  new  man,  through  self-renunciation. 
Christiani  non  nascuntur.  sedfiunt  renascendo. 

2.  Human  activity  must  have  a  place  in  the  work  of  con- 
version ;  man  has  to  play  his  due  part  in  it,  with  all  the 
energies  of  his  nature.  He  must  assist  with  his  personal 
volition ;  the  good  cannot  be  forced  upon  him,  because  a  good 
produced  in  a  magical  way  would  be  worthless,  and  no  real 
good  at  all.  No  one  enters  tlie  kingdom  by  lethargy  and 
feebleness,  the  fiiacrTai  take  it  by  force  (Matt.  xi.  12  ;  Phil, 
iii.  12).  Our  salvation  must  be  wrought  out  with  ^o/3o?  and 
Tp6fjbo<;.  So  little  is  it  the  case  that  passivity  and  weakness 
of  will  are  the  way  to  Christ,  that,  on  the  contrary,  the 
strongest  will-power  which  can  be  exercised  towards  Him  is 
requisite  in  order  to  reach  His  kingdom.  Only  it  must  be 
remembered  that  this  activity  is  not  productive ;    its  mani- 


3C8  §   11.   FAITH.       EFFECTS  OF  THE  GOSPEL. 

festation  is  of  necessity  principally  of  a  negative  kind,  con- 
sisting in  self-renunciation,  the  breaking  down  of  self-will 
and  pride,  and  the  bearing  of  the  "cross  of  Christ"  (Matt, 
xix.  29,  xvi.  24).  The  abnormal  development  that  has 
liitherto  gone  on  must  be  cancelled ;  we  must  be  willing  to 
go  back  to  the  commencement  of  that  false  by-path  along 
which  we  have  come  ;  for  a  new  and  pure  development  is 
made  possible  only  by  our  returning  to  the  beginning  and 
becoming  children  again  (Matt,  xviii.  1  ff. ;  John  iii.  5).  So 
great  is  the  self-conquest  which  is  required  here,  that  the 
apostle  often  likens  it  to  death  (liom.  vi.  2  f . ;  Gal.  ii.  19; 
Cob  ii.  12). 

The  gospel  has  the  following  effects: — (1)  It  gives  us  the 
linowlcdrjc  of  guilt  and  sin,  by  setting  over  against  us  the  holy 
prototype  we  have  in  Christ ;  the  Holy  Spirit  eXey^ei  (John 
xvi.  8).  (2)  It  avjaJcens  the  will,  that  is,  it  produces  repent- 
ance, dvacnpe(^ea6ai.  (3)  It  arouses  a  longing  desire  after 
the  righteousness  of  Christ,  after  justification  or  reconciliation, 
and  sanctification  (Matt.  v.  6).  When  a  man's  knowledge  of 
his  own  wickedness  and  his  repentance  for  it  have  come  to 
maturity  in  the  fixed  determination  to  reject  evil,  when, 
further,  he  is  aware  of  the  power  that  evil  has  over  him, — 
which  shows  that  his  resolution  or  ideal  rejection  of  evil  is 
not  yet  the  victory  over  it, — and  when,  finally,  his  sense  of 
guilt  and  punishment  is  so  quickened  that  to  remain  as  he  is 
would  be  utter  misery, — all  this  must  serve  to  drive  him 
out  of  himself,  and  draw  him  towards  the  source  whence  a 
Ijetter  life-motive  has  come  to  him.  And  now,  the  more 
simply  and  firmly  that  Christ  (in  His  entirety),  as  set  forth  in 
Scripture,  tal^es  hold  of  him,  the  more  does  he  hnoiv  that 
in  Christ  is  to  be  found  whatever  he  needs,  and  in  this  way 
the  higher  life-motive  within  him  is  encouraged  by  Christ  to 
manifest  itself  more  and  more  clearly,  just  as  the  sun  draws 
a  seed  upward  from  the  bosom  of  the  earth  (John  iii,  19  f, 
V.  38-47).  Eecognising  that  unless  new  fountains  of  life  are 
opened  up  to  him,  he  is  lost  and  must  remain  a  moral  chaos, 
he  enters  upon  that  stage  of  progress  in  which  he  sees  it  to 
be  his  moral  duty  to  accept  the  quickening  influence  of  those 
fountains  to  which  access  has  been  given.  That  is  to  say,  he 
sees  it  to  be  his  duty  to  believe,  to  renounce  himself,  and  to  sur- 


SELF-SURRENDEK  TO  CHRIST.  369 

render  himself  wholly  to  Christ.  The  conflict  and  discipline 
carried  on  by  the  believer  against  the  old  man  has  not  taken 
its  trne  form,  until  his  determination  to  throw  off  the  old  man 
includes  the  conscious  and  definite  resolve  to  submit  himself 
to  be  determined  by  Ciirist.  Where  the  will  refuses  its  con- 
sent to  this,  egoism  still  remains  unbroken,  whether  it  show 
itself  in  the  form  of  self-satisfaction  and  self-righteousness,  or 
in  the  form  of  a  self-accusation  that  is  more  severe  than  Christ 
Himself.  The  sacrifice  which  must  be  made  of  the  old  man 
does  not  only  mean  that  we  are  to  give  up  sensual  desires  and 
a  sensual  life ;  it  also  means  that  we  must  give  up  the  idea 
of  the  insignificance  of  sin, — the  idea,  that  is,  of  self -justifica- 
tion, or  that  any  help  can  be  derived  from  ourselves, — and,  on 
the  other  hand,  the  idea  that  guilt  cannot  be  pardoned  at  all. 

Moreover,  faith  ought  to  rise  above  all  these,  as  things  it 
lias  left  behind,  into  a  quite  legitimate  idealism,  in  which  it 
takes  Christ  in  His  full  significance  as  ^Mediator,  and,  on  the 
ground  of  that  real  union  we  have  with  Him  in  the  sioht  of 
God,  regards  that  which  is  as  yet  wanting  in  us  as  already 
existent,  since  it  has  a  real  existence  in  Christ.  Our  resolu- 
tion to  be  determined  wholly  by  Christ  is,  however,  very 
different  from  a  mere  quietistic  waiting  for  His  help,  or  a  mere 
striving  against  the  old  man  and  everything  which  would 
draw  us  away  from  faith ;  it  is  an  act  of  the  obedience  of 
faith,  resting  upon  the  fundamental  fact  that  we  are  drawn  to 
Christ  and  laid  hold  of  by  Him,  a  resolution  to  put  our  trust 
in  Him  as  our  Redeemer  as  well  as  our  Saviour.^ 

o.  Accordingly,  faith  in  the  evangelical  sense  is  not  merely 
historical  in  its  nature — notitia — nor  a  mere  general  assent, 
involving  no  personal  relations, — assensus, — but  along  with 
both  of  these  it  is  also  Jiducia.  This  third  element,  which 
formed  the  central  point  of  the  Reformation  and  gave  to  it 
its  characteristic  form,  includes  personal  trust  in  the  Redeemer, 
the  closest  union  with  Him,  and  willingness  to  cast  oneself 
upon  Him  alone.      It  involves  the  following : — 

(«)  The  person  of  Christ  makes  a  powerful  impression  upon 
the  feeliivjs. 

'  What  is  the  meaning  of  Luther's  '^  mere  passive"''.  It  applies  to  justifica- 
tion ;  without  our  co-operation,  before  we  believe,  God's  forgiveness  is  olfered  us 
for  the  sake  of  Christ, 

2  A 


370  §  44.  FAITH.       CEETITUDO  SALUTIS. 

(h)  On  tlie  cocjnitivc  side,  M'e  are  conscious  that  Christ  is 
worthy  of  our  confidence,  Christ,  that  is,  as  presented  in  the 
word  of  God  and  preached  by  the  Church ;  and  we  know  that 
it  is  our  duty  to  seek  salvation  in  Him,  although  lefoi^e  faith 
has  arisen  it  cannot  be  a  matter  of  actual  experience  that  in 
Hini  salvation  is  to  be  found. 

(c)  But  fiducia  is  pre-eminently  a  matter  of  volition.  It 
is  the  willingness  to  be  determined  by  Christ,  to  entrust  one- 
self to  Him  without  reserve.  In  faith  as  Jidncla  tliere  is,  to 
use  Schleiermacher  s  fine  expression,  a  general  movement  of 
the  whole  heart  and  soul  towards  Christ,  in  order  to  receive 
from  Him  salvation  and  life.  And  whoever  knocks,  to  him 
it  shall  be  opened  (Matt.  vii.  7).  In  confiding  faith  we  reach 
that  point  at  which  the  Holy  Spirit  can  bear  witness  to  our 
spirits  that  we  are  the  children  of  God,  and  arouse  in  us  that 
first  sign  of  life  which  the  new  man  gives — prayer  to  God  as 
a  forgiving  Father  (Eom.  viii.  15  ;  Gal.  iv.  6).  The  heart  is 
relieved  of  its  burden  in  the  certainty  that  sin  has  been 
wiped  away  ;  our  conscience  becomes  light  and  free,  for  we 
have  the  peace  that  passeth  all  understanding,  the  experience 
of  justification  ;  while  we  are  filled  with  joy  in  the  Hol}^ 
Spirit,  for  we  know  that  heaven  is  open,  and  that  the  way  is 
clear  to  our  Father's  house.  This  is  what  Scripture  refers  to 
when  it  says  we  are  sealed  through  the  Holy  Spirit  {a(f)pa'yk) 
(John  iii.  33,  vi.  27;  2  Cor.  i.  22  ;  Eph.  i.  13,  iv.  30; 
Eev.  vii.  3-8).  And  now  the  new  birth  has  taken  place, 
and  is  consciously  realized,  and  hence  it  is  spoken  of  in  the 
Apocalypse  as  the  giving  of  a  new  name  (ii.  17). 

This  sealing  (certitudo  salutis),  upon  which  the  Keformers 
universally  lay  so  great  stress,  is  therefore  not  to  be  identified 
with  the  act  in  which  even  an  undoubting  faith  accepts 
Christ ;  it  is  rather  a  divine  ansvjer  to  the  petition  involved 
in  faith  when  it  embraces  Christ,  an  effect  produced  within 
us  by  the  object  of  our  faith,  and  involving  the  knowledge 
both  of  the  divine  truth  of  the  object  of  faith  and  of  the 
saving  and  blessed  relation  in  which  we  stand  to  Him.  He 
who  has  it  has  no  right  to  regard  himself  as  superior  to  one 
who,  although  a  believer,  does  not  yet  possess  it.  Nevertheless 
man  naturally  desires  to  participate  in  this  certitudo  salutis, 
and  Christ  purposes  to  give  it  to  him.     When  therefore  it  is 


FAITH,  WISDOM,  AND  LOVE.  371 

wanting,  hindrances  must  exist  which  will  have  to  be  taken 
out  of  the  wav,  and  the  knowledo-e  that  it  has  been  denied 
him  is  meant  to  stimulate  the  believer  to  have  these  hind- 
rances removed.  They  will  be  found  to  disappear  more  and 
more,  the  more  that  he  accustoms  himself  to  lay  aside  dis- 
quietude, impatience,  and  restless  haste,  as  well  as  spiritual 
indolence  and  timidity,  and  to  adopt  a  simple  childlike 
state  of  mind,  in  which,  while  fully  aware  of  his  sinfulness 
and  honestly  striving  against  it,  he  can  yet  wait  cheerfull}-, 
patiently,  and  trustfully,  without  losing  his  longing  desire  for 
the  full  experience  of  salvation. 

Along  with  the  assurance  of  salvation  wrought  in  him  bv 
the  Holy  Spirit,  man  also  becomes  a  partaker  of  divine  know- 
ledge. At  one  and  the  same  time  there  is  given  him  a  real 
knowledge  of  his  own  personal  redemption,  resting  upon 
experience,  and  also  a  knowledge  of  Christ  as  the  Kedeemer 
with  whom  faith  has  brought  him  into  fellowship ;  and 
therewith  conscience  receives  a  new  position  (1  Pet.  iii.  16  ; 
1  John  iii.  19-21  ;  2  Cor.  i.  12  ;  1  Tim.  i.  5  ;  2  Tim.  i.  3  ; 
Heb.  xiii.  18).  Thus  the  inward  fruit  of  faith  is  a  knowledge 
which  is  the  basis  of  all  further  knowledge,  the  beginning  of 
divine  ivisdom.  It  is  a  knowledge  on  the  believer's  part  that 
he  is  known  and  loved  by  God  in  Christ;  further,  it  is  a 
knowledge  of  the  faithfulness,  holiness,  and  love  of  Christ 
Himself ;  and,  finally,  it  is  a  knowledge  of  what  we  become 
through  Christ  and  are  designed  to  be  in  His  kingdom. 

o  o  o 

Further,  this  knowledge  becomes  at  the  same  time  a  living 
motive  to  the  will.  Accordingly  it  furnishes  a  point  of  com- 
mencement for  love,  and  love,  by  uniting  in  itself  both  know- 
ledge and  will,  gives  us  the  union  in  principle  of  freedom  and 
conseicncc.  Faith  believes  in  the  love  of  God  in  Christ  which 
is  offered  it,  it  evinces  towards  that  love  the  trustful  rever- 
ence which  it  claims,  it  is  that  response  to  the  love  of  Christ 
which  Christ  seeks  ;  nay,  more,  as  the  thankful  acceptance  of 
love,  it  is  the  felt  need  of  love,  the  willing  consent  to  he  loved. 
Thus  in  it  egoistic  isolation  is  abandoned,  and  in  its  self- 
surrender  there  is  a  positive  inclination  towards  God  in 
Christ.  Hence  it  is  that  in  the  Gospel  of  John  our  Lord, 
when  speaking  of  faith  under  these  aspects,  calls  it  love. 
And,  finally,  there  grows  up  in  faith  a  free    desire   to   bestow 


3'72  §  45.  LOVE. 

love,  resting  upon  the  acceptance  and  experience  of  the  love 
of  God.  For  this  experience  kindles  love  in  return.  True 
faith  is  not  egoistic,  eudfemonistic,  looking  only  to  remission 
of  punishment ;  it  is  a  hunger  and  thirst  after  righteousness, 
and  after  that  holiness  with  which  it  has  been  brought  into 
close  connection  by  its  apprehension  of  Christ.  Thus  faith  is 
love  potentially  ;  that  is  to  say,  it  can  grow  into  love  by 
means  of  that  which  it  has  embraced  and  made  its  own. 

CHAPTER     SECOND. 

LOVE. 

§  4.5. 

Since  faith,  by  involving  repentance,  overcomes  sin  in  prin- 
ciple, and  since  at  the  same  time  it  opens  the  door 
of  the  heart  and  admits  the  divine  saving  power  to 
take  possession  of  a  man,  so  that  he  becomes  in  his  own 
person  the  central  seat  of  a  new  life,  it  follows  that  the 
new  man,  born  of  God,  cannot  but  image  forth  the  divine 
love.  Eeceptivity  becomes  spontaneity  and  productivity. 
The  new  creation  is  something  that  has  to  be  preserved 
and  maintained,  and  the  Spirit  of  God  becomes  tlie 
motive  power  in  the  believer's  life.  The  love  of  the 
man  who  has  Ijeen  born  into  the  new  life  turns  naturally 
towards  its  origin  first  of  all,  and  becomes  free,  reverent, 
filial  love  to  the  Three-one  God  who  first  loved  him. 
Then  springing  from  love  to  God  there  arises  in  the  new 
man  Christian  love  to  his  neighbour  and  love  to  himself, 
and  both  of  these  are  united  and  harmoniously  balanced 
in  love  to  the  kingdom  of  God. 

[LiTERATUHE. — Piothe,  Ist  cd.  i.  13.  385,  ii.  pp.  350,  371,  2nd 
ed.  i.  pp.  500-557.  Cf.  Martensen,  Christian  Ethics,  ii.  159  sq. 
Lemme,  Die  christliche  Nachstenliebe. — Ed.] 

1.  The  Pioman  Catholic  Church  is  afraid  that  unless  justi- 
fication be  made  the  reward  of  sanctification,  zeal  for  sanctili- 
cation  would  be  wanting.     And  in  consequence  of   this   fear 


FAITH  NECESSAEILY  PRODUCES  LOVE.  373 

there  are  also  Evangelical  theologians,  such  as  Hengstenberg, 
who  agree  with  the  rationalists  in  assuming  different  degrees 
of  justification,  each  one  corresponding  with  the  degree  of 
sauctificatiou  that  merits  it.  The  fear  lest  the  Evangelical 
doctrine  of  justification  might  become  an  excuse  for  indol- 
ence would  be  well  grounded,  did  we  not  hold  fast  the  close 
connection  between  faith  and  repentance.  For  those  who 
truly  believe,  it  is  so  entirely  a  matter  of  course  to  repudiate 
evil,  that  a  faith  without  repentance  would  be  a  self-contradic- 
tion. In  addition  to  this,  the  lioman  Catholic  and  rationalistic 
doctrine  fails  to  give  us  the  rationale  of  pure  love.  If  the 
purjDose  of  my  love  is  to  merit  salvation  for  myself,  then  it 
is  not  pure  love.  Such  a  love  cares  only  for  itself;  in  it  I 
make  love  a  means  for  my  own' ends;  I  do  not  make  my 
neighbour  an  end  in  himself  The  Evangelical  doctrine,  on 
the  contrary,  knows  that  nothing  can  be  thought  of  which 
lays  us  under  a  deeper  obligation  than  God's  free  love ;  that 
for  those  who  are  not  altogether  past  redemption  there  is 
nothing  more  shaming  and  humbling,  nothing  more  likely 
to  bring  us  to  sincere  remorse  and  repentance,  than  the 
prevenient  love  of  God,  which  comes  to  the  unworthy  wnth 
the  offer  of  thorough  and  complete  forgiveness.  P>angeli- 
calism  recognises  that  such  a  love  has  the  power  to  awaken 
a  kindred  love  (1  John  iv.  10),  which  will  never  think  of 
caring  merely  for  its  own  interests,  or  of  meriting  salvation — 
for  this  it  already  possesses.  As  certainly  as  faith  exists,  so 
certainly  will  it  give  birth  to  real  love.  For  it  has  surren- 
dered itself  to  Christ  to  be  determined  by  His  whole  will. 
And  it  is  part  of  the  will  of  Christ  that  love  be  wrought  in  the 
believer's  heart,  and  that  he  receive  the  power  to  love  from  the 
Spirit  of  Christ. 

2.  We  have  formerly  spoken  (§  7)  of  the  essential  nature 
of  God's  love.  Now  the  new  personality  of  the  believer 
becomes  more  and  more  conformed  to  the  image  of  God,  and 
is  therefore  conformed  to  the  divine  love.  Hence  it  has  the 
amor  covijjlacentice.  It  is  taken  possession  of  by  the  beauty 
of  the  Good ;  above  all  else,  by  that  beauty  as  it  is  seen  in 
God  and  in  Christ,  who  is  the  personal  manifestation  of  the 
lovableness  of  God.  In  like  manner  the  true  personality, 
both  our  own  and  our  neighbour's,  is  an  object  of  love,  even 


374  §  45.  LOVE.       LOVE  TO  GOD. 

if  as  yet  it  is  not  actually  realized.  With  regard  to  the 
amor  concupiscenticc  and  amor  Icncvolcntix,  these  are  the  two 
opposite  poles  of  true  love,  but  always  act  in  unison.  In  the 
amor  henevolcntim  the  tendency  is  towards  communication, 
even  self-communication,  which  tendency,  however,  must  never 
he  carried  so  far  as  to  involve  a  real  loss  to  our  personality, 
but  must  always  have  self-assertion  bound  up  with  it.  Tlie 
amor  concupiscentim,  on  the  other  hand,  tends  towards  self- 
assertion  in  one's  own  interests.  But  this  by  itself  would  be 
egoism.  Accordingly,  two  things  must  be  blended  together — 
we  must  appropriate  another  to  ourselves,  and  at  the  same 
time  make  that  other  an  end  to  ourselves,  and  communicate 
something  to  him.  And  this  is  attained  when  a  communion 
of  love  is  formed,  when  there  is  a  unio  caritatis.  For  such 
fellowship  in  love  excludes  everything  of  the  nature  either  of 
egoism  or  self-loss,  because  otherwise  there  would  be  no  real 
fellowship  at  all.  This  communion  of  love  has  its  origin  in 
God  Himself. 

3.  Love  to  God.  At  first  God  establishes  a  relation  of  love 
between  Himself  and  man  by  means  of  His  prevenient  love, 
which  expends  itself  wholly  in  giving,  and  is  received  by  faith. 
God  is  the  universal  Good,  not,  however,  in  an  abstract,  but  in 
a  personal  form, — not  as  a  mere  dead  law.  God  does  not 
only  bestow  His  grace  and  forgiveness  upon  us,  or  enter  into 
fellowship  with  us  from  His  own  side  merely  ;  He  also  enriches 
our  faith  with  the  energy  of  a  new  life,  of  a  life  of  love,  in 
which  we  offer  ourselves  back  to  God,  present  to  Him  ourselves 
and  our  powers,  and  therefore  return  His  love  freely  and 
spontaneously.  Thus  man  from  being  a  recipient  becomes 
also  a  giver,  and  God,  who  was  at  first  only  a  Giver,  accepts 
our  offering  in  order  that  a  living,  reciprocal  communion  of 
love  may  be  formed.  It  might  be  supposed,  indeed,  that  the 
divine  love  could  not  enter  into  such  a  relation  of  mutual 
exchange,  of  reciprocal  giving  and  taking.  But  as  Julius 
Mliller  rightly  says,  "  This  is  the  unfathomable  mystery  which 
is  yet  plain  to  every  simple  Christian  heart,  that  love,  which 
is  absolutely  the  highest  element  in  the  life  of  the  creature,  is 
not  subject  to  compulsion  even  from  the  omnipotent  will  of 
God  Himself.  Consequently,  love  is  a  good  which  God  cannot 
give  to  Himself,  but  can  only  receive  through  the  freedom  of  the 


FALSE  FOEMS  OF  LOVE  TO  GOD.  375 

creature ;  He  can  only  attract  man  by  His  own  infinite  love, 
can  only  fill  and  animate  man's  heart  with  the  desire  to  give 
God  his  love  by  an  act  of  his  own  free  will."  There  is,  indeed, 
a  kind  of  mysticism  which  is  nnable  to  bring  giving  and 
receiving  on  the  part  of  God  into  union  with  receiving  and 
giving  on  the  part  of  man.  And  yet  it  is  the  fact  that  the 
existence  of  a  communion  of  love  between  God  and  man 
depends  upon  each  of  them  being  both  object  and  subject, 
both  an  end  for  love  or  an  object  of  love,  and  at  the  same 
time  a  loving,  personal  power. 

{a)  Mysticism  speaks  sometimes  of  an  unselfish  love  to  God, 
which  does  not  desire  to  receive  anything  from  God,  but  only 
to  offer  itself  to  God  or  to  lose  itself  in  Him ;  a  love  which 
would  love  Him  even  were  He  to  cast  one  into  hell  (Fenelon). 
But  it  is  evident  that  this  would  really  be  a  very  selfish  sacri- 
fice to  make.  For  we  should  be  dealing  with  God  as  if,  while 
He  wished  to  be  loved  by  us.  He  Himself  were  not  love,  but 
merely  a  physical  essence,  absorbing  whatever  is  external  to 
Himself;  we  should,  in  proud  forgetfulness  of  our  own  need, 
reserve  for  ourselves  that  which  is  best  of  all,  namely,  active 
love,  and  ascribe  to  God  recipient  love  alone.  But  this 
would  be  sheer  tvilfulncss  and  ingratitude  on  our  part ;  for  v/e 
truly  love  God  only  when  we  love  Him  as  He  is,  and  there- 
fore because  He  is  related  to  us  as  loving,  nay,  because  He 
first  loved  us.  And  to  this  relation  which  subsists  between 
God  and  us  we  must  give  our  assent — as  is  demanded  by  our 
absolute  dependence  upon  God,  and  our  position  towards  Him 
as  His  creatures — in  faith.  To  do  so  is  the  first  thing  that 
is  necessary,  and  it  is  here  that  Catholic  Mysticism  and  the 
Catholic  Church  make  their  mistake.  It  is  just  our  conscious- 
ness of  the  prevenient  love  of  God,  the  consciousness  that  we 
are  loved  by  Him,  which  enkindles  our  grateful  love  to  Him 
in  return. 

(h)  The  othc7'  false  form  of  love  to  God  is  the  quietistic^ 
which  may  also  attach  itself  to  a  false  form  of  the  Evangelical 
doctrine  of  saving  faith.  Whoevei^,  after  he  has  found  all  he 
needs  in  communion  with  God  in  Christ,  chooses  now  to 
remain  in  the  enjoyment  of  his  experience,  without  proceed- 

'  Quietism  of  Molinos.     [Cf.   Heppo,    GeschicJde  cler  quktldlschen  Mystik. — 
Ed. 


37G  §  45.  LOVE.       SELF-LOVE  ANT)  SOCIAL  LOVE. 

ing  to  the  exercise  of  love  toward  God  in  return,  treats  God 
merely  as  a  means  for  his  own  personal  enjoyment.  But 
this  is  spiritual  eudcfcmonism,  in  which  God  is  no  longer 
regarded  as  an  end  or  object  of  love.  Thus  here  again  we 
have  selfishness,  in  the  form,  namely,  of  merely  recipient  love, 
just  as  before  in  so-called  "unselfish  love"  we  had  the  selfish- 
ness of  pride,  which  will  only  impart  love.  Each  of  these 
extremes,  therefore,  is  in  itself  nothing  but  egoism ;  it  is  only 
when  self-assertion  and  loving  self- surrender  are  blended 
together  that  true  love  and  communion  of  love  can  arise. 
To  say  that  a  person  loves,  is  to  say  that  he  can  be  both  end 
and  means,  that  he  can  will  himself  as  both  at  the  same 
time,  that  he  can  find  himself  in  another,  and  also  find  that 
other  in  himself.  Sucli  love  exists  originally  in  God  alone  ; 
by  virtue  of  it  God  wills  both  Himself  and  the  world,  to  the 
end  that  a  reciprocal  communion  of  life  and  love  may  be 
establislicd  between  Himself  and  it.  Lut  God  also  implants 
this  spirit  of  love  in  the  world  ;  hence,  although  the  Jirst  thing 
whicli  the  world  does  is  to  receive,  and  the  Jirst  thing  which 
God  does  is  to  give,  giving  is  not  the  sole  and  last  thing  for 
God,  nor  is  receiving  the  sole  and  last  fhing  for  man. 

4.  Self-love  and  social  love  in  relation  to  love  to  God.  When 
love  to  God  has  been  kindled  in  the  believer,  as  his  grateful 
and  reverent  response  to  God's  own  love,  it  becomes  a  motive 
within  him,  inciting  him  as  a  matter  of  duty  to  love  both 
himself  and  his  neighbour ;  nay  more,  it  affords  the  prototype 
of  what  is  here  of  special  importance,  the  union,  namely,  of 
being  in  itself,  or  self-assertion,  with  being  that  goes  out 
beyond  itself  and  finds  its  end  in  another.  True  love  to  God 
cannot  but  seek  to  love  what  He  loves,  and  to  hate  what  He 
hates.  Now  we  have  experience  in  faith  that  God  loves  us 
as  individuals ;  further.  He  loves  not  only  us,  but  also  the 
whole  world  ;  and,  finally,  He  does  not  love  what  is  merely 
iinite  in  us  and  the  world,  not  what  is  altogether  worldly  and 
sinful,  He  loves  us  and  all  men  as  designed  and  fitted  to 
be  rescued  from  the  kingdom  of  darkness,  and  to  be  built 
up  into  His  kingdom  as  living  likenesses  of  God.  Hence 
love  to  God  cannot  but  involve  true  self-love  and  social 
love. 

Let  us  now  apply  to  both  these  forms  of  love  what  has 


PERSONAL  CHARACTER  OF  LOVE.  3  77 

already  been  said  concerning  self-assertion  and  communica- 
tion. Christian  love  is  the  reconciliation  of  the  antithesis 
formed  by  self-assertion  and  self -communication,  rcceivinfj  and 
gloing,  the  'personal  and  the  universal. 

(«)  In  the  manifestation  of  love  on  the  part  of  the  believer, 
tlie  following  process  takes  place.  He  receives  the  other,  as 
it  were,  into  his  own  personality,  and  makes  him  an  end  or 
object  for  himself;  at  tlie  same  time,  he  transfers  himself  to 
that  other,  and  identifies  himself,  as  it  were,  with  the  other ; 
and  he  does  both  of  these  in  order  to  serve  the  other  and  be 
a  means  for  him.  But  all  the  wliile  the  love  of  the  Christian 
also  asserts  itself  as  love.  For  if  the  .self-sacrifice  of  love 
amounted  to  self- extinction,  the  love  would  cease  altogether 
to  be  personal.  Thus  love  has  a  double  function  to  perform, 
in  which  nothing  else  can  resemble  it.  For  the  Christian 
loves  another  just  as  he  loves  himself;  he  loves  himself  in 
the  other,  and  the  other  in  himself.  These  go  together,  for 
the  Christian  aim  is  to  establish  a  communion  of  love,  wliicli, 
while  it  includes  both  the  persons  involved,  is  higlier  than 
either  separately.  The  highest  aim  of  all  is  the  universal 
life  of  love,  the  kingdom  of  God,  in  which  every  individual 
is  ennobled,  and  all  are  united  to  one  another. 

(h)  Hence  love  also  reconciles  the  opposition  between  the 
universal  and  the  individual  or  personal.  The  individual 
person  makes  himself  an  organ  of  the  iiniucrsal,  of  that  com- 
munity of  love  which  is  the  ultimate  purpose  of  God,  and 
thus  the  opposition  is  overcome.  But  although  love  con- 
templates the  universal  good,  and,  whether  in  the  form  of 
social  or  of  self-love,  is  always  in  the  last  resort  love  to  the 
universal  good,  it  nevertheless  has  an  essentially  i^rsonal 
character,  both  in  its  objective  and  subjective  aspects.  The 
universal  Good  is  the  personal  God,  manifested  in  Christ  ;  it 
is  not  the  impersonal  law,  which  can  only  be  resj)ected  and 
cannot  be  loved.  The  law  attains  its  lovable  form,  its  beauty, 
only  vi'hen  it  becomes  personal ;  and  this  it  does  primarily  in 
God  and  visibly  in  Chri.st,  who  is  the  fairest  among  the 
children  of  men  (Augustine,  Hamann).  It  also  belongs  to 
the  nature  of  all  spiritual  excellences,  that  as  they  give  t(» 
personality  its  true  worth,  so  they  themselves  only  truly  exist 
when    they   assume  a  personal  form.      In  like   manner,  the 


378  §  45.  LOVE.       OPPOSITE  OF  SELFISHNESS. 

personal  character  of  love  is  also  exliiljited  on  the  siihjcctive 
side.  That  is  not  love  in  which  only  some  real  thing, 
something  accidental  to  the  person  is  bestowed,  while  the 
heart  is  withheld  ;  and  just  as  little  is  love  shown  when  we 
are  concerned  merely  about  the  gifts  and  benefits  to  be 
derived  from  any  one,  and  do  not  rather  seek  the  person  him- 
self as  being  himself  the  highest  gift  of  love.  But  all  the 
same  these  gifts  are,  as  we  have  pointed  out,  the  language  by 
which  love  evinces  its  desire  to  communicate  itself,  to  lay 
itself  open  to  another,  and  freely  give  him  what  it  possesses ; 
while  the  acceptance  of  the  gift,  not  only  with  the  hand  but 
with  the  heart,  is  likewise  an  act  in  which  the  heart  opens 
itself  to  receive  another — it  is  a  response  to  the  love  which  is 
presented  in  the  gift. 

5.  Love  as  the  ojjjwsite  of  sdfisliness.  Love,  as  being  the 
cardinal  active  virtue,  is  opposed  to  self-contained  egoism  or 
selfishness,  both  in  its  self-interested,  worldly  form,  and  in  its 
more  spiritual  form  of  pride.  The  loivcr  Icind  of  egoism  may 
manifest  itself  both  in  receiving  and  in  giving ;  and  this  is 
true  also  of  the  egoism  oi  imdc. 

(a)  The  lovxr  form  of  egoism  is  greedy  only  of  the  gifts  of 
love  ;  about  the  love  which  was  given  in  the  gifts,  and  is  the 
best  one  of  all,  it  does  not  concern  itself,  or  in  other  words, 
it  is  suspicious  of  the  gift  of  love.  In  it  accordingly  there  is 
no  gratitude,  in  accepting  anything  it  feels  no  answering  love. 
And  this  kind  of  egoism  may  be  shown  by  the  giver  also,  as 
when  he  gives  for  the  sake  of  thanks  or  of  human  praise  or 
reward,  or  when  1jy  his  gift  he  seeks  to  bring  the  recipient 
of  it  under  Ms 23ower.  Such  a  giving  puts  on  the  appearance 
of  love,  and  enters  love's  fellowship  in  an  external  kind  of  way, 
but  behind  it  self-interest  is  concealed. 

(Ij)  The  lovelessness  of  pride,  which  shuts  itself  off  from 
others,  may  be  exhibited  in  refusing  to  accept  as  well  as  in 
refusing  to  give.  He  who  is  rich,  M'hether  in  a  temporal  or 
spiritual  sense,  is  the  very  one  who  must  be  willing  to  accept 
love  from  those  to  whom  he  gives.  He  must  look  upon  their 
love,  which  is  only  of  value  when  it  is  a  free  gift,  as  a  good 
that  is  unrequitable  and  infinitely  higher  than  all  his  own 
outward  goods  ;  by  so  doing  he  proves  that  what  he  cares  for 
is  their  love  itself,  not  control  over  them  in  any  shape,  but 


EELATION  BETWEEN  COMMUNICATIVE  AND  llECEPTIVE  LOVE.    379 

fellowship  with  them  as  free  spirits.  Conversely,  when  any 
one  believes  that  he  has  nothing  to  give,  and  is  therefore 
imvvilling  to  accept,  because  he  dreads  being  laid  under  the 
obligation  of  manifesting  gratitude,  he  too  shuts  himself  up  in 
selfish  pride.  He  rejects  the  fellowship  of  love  that  is  offered 
him  in  the  gift,  and  fails  to  recognise  that  by  his  refusal  he 
is  actually  taking  away  something  from  the  man  who  wishes 
to  bestow  the  gift.  For  were  he  gratefully  to  accept  it, 
he  would  confer  upon  the  giver  of  it  himself  a  free  gift 
that  is  of  more  value  to  genuine  love  than  all  outward 
possessions. 

But  if  it  indeed  be  the  case  that  love  is  itself  the  best  gift 
of  all,  does  it  not  come  to  this — that  we  must  regard  the 
distinction  between  communicative  and  receptive  love  as  one 
that  is  not  valid  ?  For  the  following  considerations  may  be 
urged.  Communicating  love  is  in  itself  recipient  love  as  well, 
because  the  giver  finds  satisfaction  in  the  very  act  of  bestowing, 
and  requires  no  external  reward, — he  is  blessed  in  his  deed 
(Jas.  i.  25).  Nay  more,  if  it  is  more  blessed  to  give  than  to 
receive  (Acts  xx.  35),  it  seems  that  since  blessedness  is  the 
highest  good,  communicating  love  is  more  of  the  nature  of 
recipient  love  than  the  latter  itself  Finally,  communicating 
love  regards  itself  as  having  received  a  gift,  v/hen  its  own  gift 
is  rightly  accepted,  lovingly  acknowledged,  and  the  heart  of 
the  recipient  opened.  Conversely, — it  might  further  be 
urged,- — in  true  loving  acceptance  of  a  benefit  there  is  also  a 
real  giving  of  the  best  gift,  that  is,  of  love.  To  sum  up :  he 
who  gives  in  the  spirit  of  true  love  always  receives  as  well, 
even  should  no  gratitude  be  shown  from  the  other  side ; 
and  he  who  receives  in  the  spirit  of  true  thankfulness  has 
always  something  to  give,  namely,  grateful  love. 

Now  it  is  certainly  of  importance  to  direct  our  attention 
to  tins  equalization — as  it  may  be  called — of  communicating 
and  recipient  love,  since  true  communion  of  love  cannot  last 
without  it.  For  by  means  of  it  the  guarantee  is  given  that 
receiver  and  giver  are  each  an  end  in  himself,  that  essentially 
they  are  and  remain  equals,  both  in  themselves  and  in  the 
service  they  render  each  other.  Love  can  be  truly  bestowed 
only  when  there  is  a  real  partnership  ;  that  is  to  say,  when 
both  are  on  an  equal  footing,  when  the  relation  is  such  that 


380  §  45.  LOVE. 

pride  is  changed  into  humility,  and  even  the  poor  man,  though 
externally  in  a  lower  position,  can  do  his  part  as  an  equal  in 
mind  and  soul  if  not  in  fortune.  The  poor  man  can  make  the 
advantages  of  others  his  own  joy,  and  thus  possess  and  enjoy 
what  he  does  not  have  himself;  their  sorrows,  too,  he  can  make 
his  own.  In  a  partnership  of  this  kind  he  can  evince  pre- 
venient  and  therefore  communicating  love,  even  though  in  his 
own  person  he  is  indigent,  and  outwardly  does  nothing  but 
receive. 

Nevertheless  there  remains  a  difference  between  the  love 
which  communicates,  that  is,  which  makes  the  first  approaches 
or  sues  for  love  in  return,  and  the  love  which  receives,  or 
exhibits  gratitude.  In  the  former,  he  who  loves  seeks  to  put 
the  recipient  on  the  same  level  with  himself,  while  in  the 
latter  he  seeks  to  set  the  giver  above  himself.  Thus  both 
persons  are  engaged  in  a  noble,  loving  competition,  and  by 
this  mutual  interchange  the  living  process  of  love  moves 
onward.  We  are  reminded,  too,  of  the  necessity  of  insisting 
upon  the  difference  between  recipient  and  communicating 
love,  by  the  consideration  that  gratitude  would  cease  altogether 
were  the  recipient  to  regard  himself  as  bestowing  something. 
For  it  does  not  become  the  receiver,  but  only  the  giver,  to  look 
upon  moral  acceptance  of  a  benefit  as  being  itself  a  gift.  On 
the  other  hand,  were  the  donor  to  regard  himself  simply  as 
receiving  something  when  he  conferred  a  benefit,  he  would  be 
an  egoist,  he  would  not  make  the  recipient  the  end  or  aim  of 
his  act.^  Further,  the  receiver  must  not  remind  the  giver 
that  he,  the  recipient,  also  gives  when  he  accepts  ;  for  it  is 
only  wheii  he  feels  that  he  is  a  recipient,  and  shows  that  he 
is  grateful,  not  in  appearance  but  in  reality — it  is  only  then 
tliat  he  really  gives.  And  just  as  little  must  the  donor  bestow 
his  gift  merely  because  the  act  of  giving  brings  him  a  reward 
and  affords  him  satisfaction. 

The  two  sides  in  this  matter  are  connected  in  the  following 
way.  When  we  give,  we  must  never  do  so  in  order  to  receive;'' 
and  when,  on  the  other  hand,  we  gratefully  receive,  we  must 

^  The  j)^i'SOiHd  character  of  love  must  appear  in  the  object  to  which  love  is 
directed  and  the  gilt  that  is  bestowed,  as  well  as  in  the  disposition  from  which 
love  springs. 

-  "He  that  givetli,  let  him  do  it  with  simplicity"  (Rom.  xii.  8). 


LOVE  THE  UNITY  OF  THE  PRODUCTIVE  VIRTUES.  381 

never  have  the  consciousness  that  by  our  acceptance  we  are 
giving  something,  for  this  would  poison  gratitude  and  make 
it  a  mere  pretence.  On  the  contrary,  communicating  love  is 
genuine  love  only  when  it  gives  as  if  it  were  to  receive  nothing 
in  return  (Matt.  v.  42-47),  it  has  attained  its  end  when  it  is 
solicitous  for  another's  welfare  (Phil.  i.  4) ;  and  grateful  love, 
again,  actually  gives  while  receiving  only  when  it  receives  as 
if  it  were  giving  nothing,  for  it  on  its  part  has  attained  its 
end  when  it  acknowledges  another's  love.  Only  in  this  way 
can  the  love  that  bestows  be  manifested  on  the  one  side  and 
loved  on  the  other,  only  in  this  way  can  the  person  of  another 
and  fellowship  with  him  be  made  the  aim  both  of  giver  and 
receiver.  The  self-forgetl'ulness  of  love  forgets  egoism  and 
isolation,  but  it  does  not  forget  love  and  love's  fellowship. 
In  love  we  seek  to  enter  into  communion  with  a  fellow-being 
and  become  a  sharer  both  of  his  sorrows  and  his  joys ;  and  in 
doing  so,  we  find  that  our  self-surrender  gives  us  what  we  did 
not  seek — it  enriches  and  completes  our  own  personal  life. 
And  this  takes  place  on  both  sides ;  we  tender  ourselves  to 
another  to  advance  as  it  were  and  develop  his  individual 
being  and  character,  and  we  receive  this  development  our- 
selves. 

6.  We  have  seen  that  in  love  the  individual  or  personal  is 
brought  into  union  with  the  universal,  while  the  difference 
between  them  is  still  maintained.  We  have  also  seen  that 
love  is  the  union  of  giving  and  receiving,  of  communicating  to 
another  what  is  our  own,  and  participating  in  what  belongs  to 
him.  And  this  union  takes  place  as  follows — we  conceive 
of  an  evil  that  affects  others  as  also  affecting  ourselves,  while 
we  regard  a  good  that  belongs  to  us  as  belonging  also  to 
others,  as  intended  for  our  brethren  as  well  as  ourselves.  (A 
striking  illustration  of  what  has  just  been  said  occurs  iu 
Acts  iv.)  But  in  addition  to  this,  love  is  also  the  unity 
(avaKe^dXaioiai<i)  of  all  those  commandments  that  address 
themselves  to  our  spontaneity  and  productivity ;  it  is  the 
principle  of  all  spontaneous  and  productive  virtues,  the  virtues 
that  are  manifested  amid  the  manifold  relations  and  circum- 
stances upon  which  Christian  vAsdovi  must  be  brought  to 
bear  (Eom.  xiii.  9,  10  ;  Matt.  xxii.  36-40  ;  John  xiii.  34  ft".  ; 
1  John  ii.  5  ;   1  Cor.  xiii.;  Mark  xii.  31).     Where  love  is  not 


382  §  4C.  CHRISTIAN  WISDOM. 

present,  we  often  see  form  and  contents  separated  from  each 
other.  On  the  one  hand,  the  right  act  or  work  may  be 
purposed  while  the  right  disposition  is  absent ;  and,  on  the 
other,  the  right  moral  disposition  may  be  present,  but  devoid 
of  contents — that  is  to  say,  the  work  is  not  done  which  the 
occasion  demands.  But  love  unites  both  form  and  contents. 
For  when  it  is  energetic,  it  does  not  rest  satisfied  with  mere 
good  wishes ;  it  wills  a  good  that  is  actually  to  be  carried  into 
effect,  and  hence  it  impels  us  to  know  truly  and  definitely 
what  those  ends  are  which  ought  to  be  realized.  This  leads 
us  to  our  thirel  chapter. 

With  regard,  moreover,  to  the  form  of  moral  action,  when 
we  consider  the  motive — that  is,  the  inducement  to  action 
when  taken  up  into  consciousness — and  the  motive  'power — 
that  is,  this  inducement  when  it  has  passed  over  into  the 
vyill — we  see  that  in  love  to  God  in  Christ  both  motive 
and  motive  j^ower  arc  united.  For  the  motive  is  God's  love 
to  us  which  He  has  manifested  in  Christ ;  and  this  love,  as 
revealed  in  Christ,  does  not  remain  for  the  Christian  a  mere 
external  object,  it  becomes  an  end  for  his  activity,  and  he 
devotes  himself  to  its  service  with  responsive  love.  And 
the  love  which  he  gives  in  return  means  that  the  love  revealed 
in  Christ  has  taken  possession  of  his  feelings  and  his  heart, 
has  seized  upon  and  animated  his  will,  and  has  thus  become 
the  motive  povjer  that  inspires  his  life. 


CHAPTER    THIRD. 

CHRISTIAN     WISDOM. 
§46. 

As  faith  (§  44)  directs  itself  to  Christ  who  is  the  perfect 
law,  the  law  of  I'aith  and  life,  and  by  accepting  Him 
becomes  the  cardinal  receptive  virtue ;  further,  as 
Christian  love  (§  45)  is  the  cardinal  virtue  of  the 
free,  productive  will :  so  Christian  wisdom  is  the  (spon- 
taneous and  productive)  cardinal  virtue  of  the  intellect. 
United  with  love  it  becomes  ideal,  productive,  virtuous 


GNOSIS.  3S6 

energy ;  its  immediate  aim  is  the  chief  Good ;  and  this 
it  conceives  in  two  forms,  both  as  already  come  and  as 
ever  in  the  process  of  coming,  Tlius  true  wisdom  is  the 
same  as  Christian  hope,  which  is  neither  ignorance  con- 
cerning the  future  nor  uncertainty  and  mere  empty 
desire,  but  is  the  principle  of  that  true  Christian  view 
of  the  world  which  is  quickened  by  love  into  fruitful 
activity. 

1.  Love,  without  wisdom  to  determine  what  aims  are  to  be 
pursued  and  what  means  are  to  be  employed  in  securing 
them,  could  not  be  morally  productive,  but  would  remain  a 
mere  inward  loving  disposition  (§  43.  2).  It  must  of  necessity, 
however,  be  accompanied  by  knowledge,  for  it  arises  out  of 
faith,  which  contains  knowledge  in  a  germinal  form  (Eph. 
i.  17)  (§  44),  and  which  brings  us  into  fellowship  with  Christ, 
who  communicates  Himself  to  the  intellect  as  well  as  to  the 
feelings  and  will.  It  is  only  when  love  is  filled  with  wisdom 
that  it  can  8oki/j,6^6iv  to.  hia^epovTa}  those  "excellent  things" 
to  which  it  must  devote  its  energy.  Thus  it  is  when  love  is 
united  with  wisdom  that  it  becomes  the  fruitful  mother  of  all 
those  moral  virtues  which  address  themselves  each  to  its  own 
specific  w^ork.  From  Christian  wisdom,  which  is  essentially 
and  purely  ethical  in  character  and  aim  (Jas.  iii.  1 3),  we  must 
distinguish — 

(«)  Gnosis  (1  Cor.  viii.  1,  xiii.  8).  Gnosis  is  not,  like 
.wisdom,  a  matter  of  universal  Christian  duty ;  it  is  a  gift  of 
grace  bestowed  upon  certain  individuals,  and  intended  to  be 
used  by  them  for  the  edification  of  the  whole  community.  If 
it  were  something  merely  intellectual  as  such,  without  an 
ethical  and  religious  spirit  (Col.  ii.  18 ;  1  Tim,  i.  6,  7,  iv,  1  ff.; 
Jas.  iii.  15),  then  knowledge  or  wisdom  of  this  kind  would 
be  contradictory  to  faith  (1  Tim.  i,  19),  which  is  the  root  of 
all  true  knowledge.  It  would  be  valueless,  it  would  be 
eVtVeio?  even  should  it  talk  of  heavenly  things,  it  would 
remain  psychical  and  even  carnal,  though  it  might  appear 
to  be  super-spiritual  (1  Cor.  ii,  13;  Jude  10;  Bai/xovicuSr]!;, 
Jas.  iii,  15), 

'  Rom.  xii.  2,  ii.  18  ;  Phil.  i.  10. 


384  §  4G.  CHRISTIAN  WISDOM.       HOPE. 

{h)  Wisdom  must  also  be  distinguished  from  Christian 
■prudence  (Luke  xvi,  1  f.,  Parable  of  the  Steward),  tppovrjai^. 
The  latter  has  to  do  with  individual  cases  as  they  arise ;  it 
has  to  comprehend  these  intelligently,  and  deal  with  them  in 
a  manner  suitable  to  the  time  and  circumstances  of  their 
occurrence  ;  its  s^jhere  is  the  world  of  means,  while  wisdom 
is  concerned  above  everything  else  with  the  determination 
of  ends. 

Xow  Christian  wisdom,  from  which  aw^poavvq  derives  its 
strength,  is  above  all  things  knowledge  of  the  uXi]6eLa,  which 
is  revealed  in  Christ.  It  springs,  therefore,  from  faith,  which 
is  called  the  "eyes  of  the  heart"  (Eph.  i.  17,  18).  It  is 
the  knowledge  of  God's  love  as  the  absolutely  true  reality  ; 
it  is  consequently  the  knowledge  of  the  absolute,  permanent, 
and  divine  world-goal,  the  supreme  ideal,  the  highest  good  ; 
and  in  this  knowledge  also  the  means  are  pointed  out  by 
which  the  good  is  to  be  realized,  for  the  end  determines  the 
way  by  which  the  end  is  reached.  Cognition  in  its  receptive 
form,  or  faith,  is  followed  by  cognition  in  its  active  form,  or 
wisdom.  Wisdom  now  takes  the  torch  of  that  higher  know- 
ledge of  God  and  His  love  which  has  come  through  faith, 
carries  it  into  the  inward  sphere  of  self-consciousness  and  into 
the  outward  sphere  of  the  world  around  us,  and  teaches  us  to 
understand  more  and  more  the  divine  thoughts  which  have 
been  wrought  into  these  spheres,  to  recognise  their  abundance, 
and  to  comprehend  their  connection  with  each  other.  But  all 
the  while,  amid  the  diversity  of  the  knowledge  thus  acquired, 
unity  is  preserved  by  the  teleological  direction  that  is  given 
to  it  throughout,  since  it  is  all  brought  into  relation  to  the 
highest  good,  the  final  consummation,  which  is  the  centre  and 
aim  of  all  our  efforts. 

Further,  so  far  as  faith  has  not  only  a  general  knowledge 
of  the  goodness  and  love  of  God  and  Christ,  ])ut  is  also  assured 
of  the  unchangeableness  and  faithfulness  of  that  love,  we  have 
a  knowledge  of  the  future  given  us  in  germ,  and  so  Christian 
wisdom  becomes  hope.  The  invincible  power  and  faithfulness 
of  the  divine  love  is  our  surety  that  the  final  consummation 
will  be  reached,  the  world-goal  attained.  Christian  wisdom 
is  practically  fruitful  just  because  at  its  highest  point  it  is 
always  Christian  hope.      And  this  involves  that  we  not  oidy 


FAITH  AND  HOPE.  385 

have  the  clear  knowledge  that  the  consummation  is  still  at 
a  distance,  but  that  we  also  have  the  no  less  clear  and  certain 
knowledge  that  the  good  is  real,  and  is  not  hoped  and  striven 
.for  in  vain ;  it  is  the  knowledge,  in  fact,  that  the  energy 
resident  in  the  kingdom  of  God  is  sufficient  for  its  realization. 
Thus  wisdom  as  hope  effects  the  transition  from  virtue  as  an 
inw^ard  power  to  the  luorh  to  which  virtue  is  called,  to  actual 
labour  for  the  coming  of  the  kingdom  of  God.  And  this 
it  does  in  reliance  upon  the  fact  that  the  kingdom  has  already 
come,  a  fact  of  which  faith  is  assured,  and  to  which  it  bears 
witness. 

It  is  true  that  hope  looks  to  the  future, — as  faith  looks  to 
the  past,  to  the  historical  revelation  made  in  Christ;  but  it  does 
more,  it  overcomes  the  limits  of  time  before  us,  just  as  faith 
overcomes  those  which  are  behind.  As  that  would  not  be  a 
living  faith  which  regarded  Christ  merely  as  belonging  to  the 
past,  as  a  mere  figure  in  history, — for,  on  the  contrary,  it  is 
the  function  of  faith  to  make  the  past  live  in  the  present 
as  an  object  of  present  experience, — so  that  would  not  be 
Christian  hope  which  looked  upon  the  End  or  the  World-goal 
as  something  merely  future,  entirely  absent,  and  therefore 
without  present  efficacy.  For  then  tliere  would  be  no  certainty 
regarding  that  goal,  and  what  it  actually  is ;  and  without  this 
there  would  not  be  Christian  hope.  But  Christian  hope 
has  a  knowledge  of  the  future  and  what  the  future  contains, 
since  even  now  the  chief  good  is  present  to  it  in  Christ,  and 
in  knowing  Him  it  knows  one  who  in  His  spiritual  supremacy 
holds  the  future  in  His  hands.  It  is  true  that  the  object  of 
hope  lacks  visibility,  that  is,  it  lacks  the  element  of  external 
reality'or  realization,  and  in  this  respect  faith  and  hope  are 
alike.  Neither  of  them  is  sight ;  they  are,  on  the  contrary, 
wholly  different  from  it.  But,  in  rising  above  what  is  present 
and  visible  to  their  invisible  object,  they  have  emancipated 
themselves  from  the  power  of  sense,  and  are  conscious  of  the 
fact.  Thus  by  means  of  faith  and  hope  the  past  and  the 
future  are  incorporated  with  the  present,  in  the  inward  life  of 
the  new  free  Christian  spirit,  the  life  of  love  (1  Cor.  xiii.  13). 
And  hence  the  believer  possesses  an  assured,  joyful,  and  kingly 
spirit,  and  enters  upon  the  enjoyment  and  activities  of  the  life 
eternal,  a  life  that  is  in  time  and  yet  above  time  {^wr}  alcavio^), 

2  B 


386         §  4G.    CHEISTIAN  WISDOM.       CHARACTER  OF  HOPE. 

2.  Peter  is  the  apostle  of  Iwpc}     (1  Pet.  i.  3-5,  9,  13,  21, 
iii.  5,  15.)     With  him,  hope  is  not  merely  comfort  and  con- 
solation in  sufferings;  it  is  not  idle,  on  the  contrary  (i.  13), 
it  is  a  living  principle  that  stimulates  us  to  gird  up  the  loins 
of  our  mind.     It  is  opposed  alike  to  cowardice  and  to  that 
fanciful  enthusiasm  which  would  fain  flee  to  the  goal  without 
travelling  the    sober   road   of   work.       It   is   temperate  and 
sedate  (iii.  15,  i.  13,  iv.  7,  v,  8),  far  removed  from  self-made 
fancies.     It  is  not  the  mere  natural  outcome  of  a  gay  temper  ; 
it  is  submissive  to  God,  willing  to  suffer,  and  yet  amid  all  the 
sufferings  of  time  is  sure  of  the  consummation  that  will  be 
reached.      Standing  in  view  of  the  eternal,  divine  ideal,  it 
gives  the  Christian,  on  the  one  hand,  the  sense  of  pilgrimage, 
of  distance  from  his  home,  and  forbids  him  to  build  everlast- 
ing habitations  here ;  while,  on  the  other,  being  assured  of 
the  future,  it  enters  heartily  into  the  present,  is  practically 
fruitful,  and  like  a  faithful  steward  puts  its  hand  honestly 
to  its  work  (1  Pet.  ii.  11  f.,  iv.  10,  11,  16,  iii.  17).     For  it 
knows  that  its  work  will  be  rewarded.      Christian  hope  also 
imparts  its  tone  to   our   love  for  our  fellow  -  creatures,  and 
makes    our   work    among    them    of    lasting    value.       For   it 
enhances  the  worth  of  individuals  by  taking  their  future  into 
account.     It  teaches  us  to  treat  them  with  confidence.    When 
we  distrust  a  man,  we  depress  him,  enfeeble  him,  and  thrust 
him  away  from  us ;  when  we  confide  in  him,  we  raise  and 
encourage  him.      Christians  love  their  brethren  as  those  who 
are  partakers  of  the  same  hope  as  themselves  (1  Pet.  i,  22, 
iv.   8).       Hope  embraces  also  the  community,  the  spiritual 
household  of  G-od ;  it  likewise  embraces  those  who  have  yet 
to  become  brethren,  and  lays  claim  to  our  love  and  zeal  on 
their  behalf  (ii.  9,  10,  12). 

3.  The  object  of  Christian  hope  is,  speaking  generally,  the 
chief  good,  and  therefore  everything  that  belongs  to  it.  And 
this  embraces — 

(a)  The  perfection  of  the  individual  character,  its  emanci- 
pation from  error  and  sin,  and  its  harmonious  development. 
It  is  no  light  task  that  is  set  before  the  Christian  in  his  daily 
life,  to  hold  it  as  a  matter  of  divine  certainty  that  he  both 
can  and  is  intended  to  become  sinless  and  holy.  The  ever- 
^  Cf.  Weiss,  Petrinischer  Lehrhec/rif. 


OBJECT  TO  WHICH  HOPE  IS  DIRECTED.  887 

recuniug  experience  which  we  have  of  sin,  which  continues 
to  break  out  in  spite  of  all  our  resolutions,  leads  us  too  readily 
to  the  tacit  supposition  that  sin  makes  a  holy  life  altogether 
impossible  for  us  on  earth.  And  although  such  a  belief  may 
at  first  humble  and  sadden  us,  yet  it  is  very  apt  to  result  in 
a  lowering  of  our  ideal,  and  in  a  moral  levity  that  makes  us 
Loo  lenient  with  our  faults.  Christian  hope  alone  can  obviate 
these  errors,  both  the  Manichajan  and  the  Pelagian.  For  by 
setting  our  goal  vividly  before  us,  and  thus  showing  us  all 
that  we  yet  need  in  order  to  have  our  imperfections  remedied 
("hope  that  is  seen  is  not  hope,"  Eom.  viii.  24),  it  opposes 
our  indolence,  and  calls  upon  us  to  exercise  vigorously  our 
will  and  our  love. 

Further,  since  in  faith  hope  has  already  tasted  the  airap-^T] 
of  the  Spirit  (Eom.  viii.  23),  and  of  perfection,  as  an  earnest 
of  that  which  is  still  lacking ;  or,  in  other  words,  since  through 
faith  hope  sees  in  the  kingdom  of  God,  as  it  has  already 
come,  the  surety  for  that  which  is  yet  to  come,  it  inspires 
love  with  the  confidence  of  victory,  and  fills  it  with  good 
courage  (1  Cor.  xiii.  7  ;  Eph.  i.  11-14;  Phil.  i.  6,  ii.  13)  and 
Christian  joy,  xapd  (Phil.  ii.  18,  iv.  4).  There  is  some  truth 
in  what  Spinoza  says  when  he  calls  tristitia  the  mother  of 
much  evil,  especially  of  the  powerlessness  of  good  impulses. 
Only  he  omits  to  point  out  the  way  to  true  joy.  This  lies 
in  Christian  hope.  In  it  that  which  humbles  us,  viz.  our 
dissatisfaction  with  our  actual  state,  becomes  a  negative  factor 
in  our  progress,  an  incentive  to  prosecute  our  own  self- 
improvement  with  vigour.  Thus  tristitia,  when  incorporated 
with  the  whole  moral  nature  of  the  Christian,  is  deprived  of 
all  that  would  have  an  enfeebling  effect,  and  what  remains 
has  only  a  salutary  influence.  It  becomes  godly  sorrow, 
which  is  not  irreconcilable  with  inward  Christian  blessedness, 
but  is  at  one  with  it,  and  necessarily  promotes  its  richer  and 
richer  development  (2  Cor.  vii.  10;  Eom.  viii.  15-17,  23-25, 
28-30). 

(h)  But  Christian  hope,  allied  with  love,  also  extends  'beyond 
the  individual.  It  takes  in  the  Chief  Good  in  the  whole  of  its 
extent,  and  hence  it  embraces  nature  and  the  spirit-world,  and 
the  final  perfection  of  both  in  and  along  with  each  other  (Pk,om. 
viii.  18-22  ;  1  Cor.  xv.  23-28,  40-50),  as  well  as  the  various 


388  §  47.    CHRISTIAN  VIEW  OF  THE  WOELD. 

iudividual  excellences  that  belong  to  the  ethical  spheres  of 
life.  Accordingly,  Christian  eschatology  becomes  an  active 
element  in  Christian  virtue.  Hope  presents  ns  with  an  image 
of  the  individual  and  of  moral  communities  in  their  perfection, 
and  by  this  means  the  future  is  made  an  operative  power  in 
the  present,  and  its  realization  is  brought  about.  Under  the 
old  covenant,  prophecy  was  sporadic  and  momentary ;  under 
the  new,  hope  furnishes  every  true  believer  with  the  prophetic 
spirit.  For  Christian  hope  is  not  mere  subjective  wishing, 
nor  does  it  mean  nescience  with  regard  to  what  the  future 
contains, — such  a  nescience  as  we  are  entertained  with  oftener 
than  is  desirable  in  New  Year  sermons ;  it  possesses  certain 
knowledge  of  the  essential  contents,  the  v7r6arTacn<i  (Heb.  xi.  1), 
of  the  future,  and  above  all,  it  is  knowledge  concerning  that 
which  is  most  remote — the  final  end  of  all  things. 

§  47.   The  Christian  View  of  the  World. 

■Christian  wisdom,  united  with  love  and  based  upon  faith, 
leads  us  to  a  view  of  the  world  that  is  opposed  both  to 
Pessimism  and  Optimism.  As  against  the  former,  the 
Christian  knows  through  faith  that  the  supreme  good 
has  already  come  and  is  present  in  the  world ;  as  against 
the  latter,  he  recognises  that  the  chief  good  has  still  to 
come,  and  has  yet  to  be  realized  through  love.  Thus, 
through  Christian  wisdom  in  the  form  of  hope,  love  is 
guided  to  the  particular  work  which  must  be  performed, 
in  order  that  that  part  of  the  chief  good  may  be  realized 
whose  time  of  realization  has  come.  And  so  love  effects 
the  transition  from  virtue  as  an  inward  impulse  to  outward 
virtuous  deeds  or  acts  of  duty,  and  in  these  manifests  its 
productive  activity.  And  this  takes  place  in  such  a 
way  that  every  true  act  of  virtue  is  a  product  of  the  ivholc 
virtuous  energy  of  the  Christian,  and  in  it  faith,  love,  and 
hope  are  in  essential  union  with  each  other. 

Note. — Leibnitz,  in  his  Theodicy,  has  tried  to  explain  the  e\'il 
— both  moral  and  physical — that  is  in  tlie  world,  without  pre- 
judice to  the  wisdom  and  goodness  of  God,  by  maintaining  that 


OPTBIISM  AND  PESSIMISM.  389 

this  is  the  best  of  all  possible  worlds.  Here  the  gooduessand 
wisdom  of  God  are  acknowledged,  but  at  the  same  time  it  is 
asserted  that  a  world  without  evil  is  an  impossibility,  even  for 
the  Divine  Omnipotence.  This  view  was  called  Optimism.  But 
Optimism  in  this  sense  is  different  from  what  we  here  mean  by 
the  word,  and  from  what  it  is  usually  taken  to  mean.  It  com- 
monly denotes  a  way  of  thinking  that  takes  a  superficial  view 
of  physical  and  even  of  moral  evil.  [Optimism  of  this  latter 
hind  is  advanced  by  Strauss  in  Der  alte  unci  der  neue  Glmibc, 
Herbert  Spencer  in  First  Princi]ples,  especially  §  176,  and  by 
other  materialists. — Ed.] 

So  far  as  Leibnitz  holds  that  finitude  in  itself  necessarily 
introduces  evil,  and  that  the  world  therefore,  as  long  as  it 
remains  finite,  i.e.  as  a  world,  must  be  afflicted  v/ith  evils, — to 
this  extent  his  theory  contains  a  pessimistic  element,  resting 
upon  a  species  of  dualism ;  and  this  remains  true  although  he 
holds  that  good  preponderates  over  evil.  The  Evangdinui  der 
armcn  Sccle  expresses  the  same  pessimistic  idea  when  it  main- 
tains that  God  cannot  be  tliought  of  as  omnipotent,  if  we  hold 
fast,  as  we  must  do,  to  His  goodness  in  presence  of  the  evil  that 
is  in  the  world.  Others,  like  Stuart  Mill,  come  to  the  conclu- 
sion that  we  must  doubt  whether  God  exists  at  all ;  since,  if  He 
did  exist.  He  would  necessarily  be  all-powerful,  and  so  would 
not  endure  the  mass  of  evil  that  is  in  the  world.  Atheism  is 
also  the  basis  upon  which  Schopenhauer  and  Hartmann  have 
raised  their  pessimistic  theories ;  and  among  Oriental  systems 
the  same  thing  holds  good  of  Buddhism,  which  is  originally  a 
system  of  philosophy.  The  torment  and  misery  in  the  world, 
which  would  make  its  non-existence  a  blessing,  are  held  to 
consist  in  this, — that  the  human  will  must  necessarily  always 
will  something,  and  that  everything  which  it  does  will  must, 
in  the  nature  of  things,  be  individual,  and  so  cannot  bring  satis- 
faction to  the  soul,  but  only  satiety  and  discomfort.  Existence 
always  involves  particularity  and  finitude,  and  these  are  of 
necessity  accompanied  with  misery,  suffering,  and  a  painful 
sense  of  want,  since  the  particular  or  individual  is  not  the 
whole.  Among  leading  exponents  of  this  form  of  pessimism  are 
Taubert  and  Volkelt.  (The  latter,  in  his  Das  Unheivusstc  und 
der  Pessimismus,  attempts  to  show  his  connection  with  Hegel.) 
[Frauenstadt.  Bahnsen,  Zur  FJiilosophie  der  Geschichtc.  Main- 
lander,  Fhilosophie  der  Erlosung.  Plumacher,  Der  Kampf  iim's 
Unhewusste  (pp.  117-150,  Litteraturangaben). — Ed.] 

Among  the  opponents  of  Pessimism  are — Haym,  Frcussische 
Jahrhiicher,  1873,  Nos.  1-3.  Weygoldt,  Kritik  des  pMlos.  Fes- 
siiiiismus. 

[Eehmke,  Glossen  zu  Hartmann  s  Flianomenologie.     Zeitschr. 


390  §  47.    CHRISTIAN  VIEW  OF  THE  WORLD. 

fuT  Philoso^hie  unci  philosophiscJie  Kritik,  1879,  No.  2.  Der 
Pessimismus  vnd  die  Sittenlehre,  1883.  Michelis,  Philosophu  des 
Bewusstscins.  'EVjYSiTd,  JTartmann's  Philosophie  dcs  Unheunissten, 
1876.  Golther,  Der  moderne  Pessimismus,  edited  by  Vischer. 
E.  Ptieiderer,  Der  Pessimismus.  Lasson,  Pluilosophische  Monats- 
heft,  1879,  Nos.  6  and  7.  Gass,  Optimismus  und  Pessimismus. 
A.  Schweizer,  Philosophie  d.  Unhewusstcn.  Ztschr.  f.  wiss.  Theol. 
1873,  p.  407  sq.  Huber,  Die  religiose  Fragc.  Secretan,  La 
nouvcauM  metaphysique.  Phil,  de  Vinconscient.  Revue  chr^tienne, 
1872.  Sommer,  Per  Pessimismus  und  die  Sittenlehre.  Christ, 
Der  Pessimismus  und  die  Sittenlehre.  My  article,  "  Hartmann's 
pessimistische  Philosophie,"  Studien  und  Kritlken.,  1881,  No.  1. 
Prantl,  Die  BcrccJitigung  des  Optimismus.  Euckeii,  Geschichte  u. 
Kritih  d.  Grundhegriffe,  p.  236  sq.  Hoekstra,  Dc  Tegenstelling 
van  Optimisme  en  Pessimisme,  1880. — Ed.] 

Frank  advances  the  idea  that  Pessimism  is  the  truth  of  the 
life  of  unbelief.  But  it  is  Martensen  especially  who  has  given 
an  ethical  estimate  of  Pessimism  as  it  appears  within  Chris- 
tianity {Christian  Ethics,  vol.  i.  p.  164  sq.,  vol.  ii.  p.  199  sq.).  The 
fundamental  error  in  these  systems  is  that  liniteness  is  looked 
upon  as  necessarily  involving  imperfection.  That  is  to  say,  all 
determination,  without  which  there  could,  of  course,  be  no 
world  at  all,  is  regarded  as  negation,  instead  of  as  a  specific  mode 
of  being ;  and  conversely,  the  unlimited  or  indeterminate  is 
regarded  as  true  and  perfect  being.  But  such  being,  like  Nir- 
vana,  cannot  be  distinguished  from  mere  nothingness.  These 
form.s  of  Pessimism,  closely  connected  as  they  are  with  Dualism 
or  Atheism,  are  for  us  made  untenable  by  the  Christian  doctrine 
of  God. 

However,  there  is  a  certain  trutli  in  this  pessimistic  view  of 
the  world,  if  only  it  be  taken  apart  from  the  grounds  upon 
which  it  is  made  to  rest.  That  is  to  say,  if  the  world  be  con- 
sidered as  it  is,  apart  from  redemption,  apart  from  the  salt  of 
Christianity  which  preserves  it  from  corruption,  then  to  sober 
observation  penetrating  to  the  truth  behind  the  appearance  of 
things,  it  is  a  state  of  misery,  a  huge  grave  ;  it  is  that  vale  of 
tears  wdiich  the  Preacher  saw  it  to  be  when  he  declared  that 
the  true  verdict  upon  the  pre-Christian  world  was,  "  all  is 
vanity."  But  revealed  religion,  even  in  Old  Testament  times, 
made  a  great  advance  beyond  all  the  positions  of  absolute 
Pessimism,  by  referring  the  evil  that  is  in  the  world  neither  to 
God  uor  to  a  power  inaependent  of  God,  but  to  human  sin,  and 
by  deriving  death  from  the  same  source.  By  this  means,  it  is 
true,  man  is  made  to  suffer  a  still  deeper  pain  than  the  so-called 
world-pain,  with  its  complainings ;  for  physical  evil  reminds  us 
of  human  guilt,  and  is  thereby  armed  with  a  still  sharper  sting. 


THE  TWO  FORMS  OF  OPTIMISM.  391 

A  greater  than  physical  evil  is  brought  to  light  in  the  world, 
viz.  moral  evil.  Nevertheless,  faith  in  God  is  now  preserved, 
faith  in  His  goodness  and  power,  and  this  affords  a  resting- 
place  for  hope.  Evil  is  now  regarded,  not  as  something  neces- 
sary, due  to  existence  itself,  but  as  relatively  accidental,  since 
it  is  made  to  depend  upon  the  sin  and  the  freedom  of  man. 

Finally,  the  evils  that  do  exist  would  themselves  be  bearable, 
if  only  the  greatest  of  them  all,  viz.  guilt,  were  wiped  away 
through  divine  forgiveness.  For  the  sting  of  evil,  which  con- 
sists in  its  being  punishment,  would  then  be  taken  away,  and 
evils  themselves,  while  still  continuing  to  exist,  would  be  looked 
upon  as  a  means  of  education  and  purification,  and  consequently 
as  a  good.  And  if,  besides,  the  power  of  sin.  as  well  as  of  guilt 
were  broken  by  God,  then  all  other  evils  would  be  checked  at 
their  source,  and  hope  might  rejoice  in  the  prospect  of  a  condi- 
tion of  things  in  which  evils  will  have  wholly  disappeared.  This 
is  the  Christian  view  of  the  world.  And  it  is  opposed  not  only 
to  the  error  of  Pessimism  but  to  that  of  Optimism  as  well. 
Although  the  Christian  jjrinciplc  is  in  the  world,  and  thus  the 
salvation  of  the  w^orld  is  something  real  and  present,  we  must 
not  overlook  the  work  that  has  still  to  be  performed  and  the 
battle  that  has  still  to  be  fought  before  victory  is  won,  nor  must 
we  lull  ourselves  into  premature  contentment  with  our  own 
state  and  that  of  the  world.  Even  in  Christian  times  it  is 
possible  to  find  mild  forms  of  Optimism  and  Pessimism  at  work, 
which  alike  exercise  an  enfeebling  and  enervating  effect,  and 
are  therefore  most  pernicious.  But  Christian  hope  is  able  to 
withstand  both  of  these  errors  ;  we  have  only  to  turn  to  it  and 
then  our  moral  vigour  is  restored,  and  true  Christian  motives 
aroused. 

1.  Along  with  hope  there  arises  the  Christian  vieiv  of  the 
Woiid.  Its  character  is  clearly  brought  out  by  its  opposi- 
tion both  to  Optimism  and  Pessimism.  Optimism  is  moral 
apathy,  and  takes  two  forms.  On  the  one  hand,  it  may  over- 
estimate earthly  well-being  and  its  influence  upon  morality ; 
on  the  other,  it  may  U7ulervalue  the  -power  of  evil  in  the 
world,  refuse  to  look  at  evil,  disregard  its  power,  and  lull 
itself  to  sleep  with  rose-coloured  illusions  concerning  the 
power  and  practice  of  virtue  in  the  world.  In  one  word,  it 
treats  the  world  and  the  individual  person  ideally  :  it  does  not 
take  them  as  they  are,  but  anticipates  their  perfection  in  its 
subjective  imaginings.  When  those  who  have  arrived  at  such 
hasty  satisfaction  with  everything  proceed  to  act,  they  would 
fain  overleap  the  stages  which  must  first  be  traversed  before 


392      §  47.    CHRISTIAN  VIEW  OF  THE  WORLD.       THE  TWO  FORMS 

the  end  is  reached,  and  so  their  action  is  applied  at  the  wrong 
place.  And  just  as  their  conceptions  of  the  nearest  aims  to 
be  pursued  and  the  means  to  be  employed  are  wrongly- 
formed,  so  no  result  follows  their  efforts.  Optimism  is  morally 
superficial ;  it  lacks  depth  of  earth,  7?}  ttoWt]  (Matt.  xiii.  5, 
20).  Those  who  from  love  of  ease  would  like  to  flee  at  once 
to  the  goal,  make  no  progress,  because  they  disdain  to  labour 
in  the  sweat  of  their  face,  and  to  mount  upward  step  by  step. 
In  short,  Optimism  is  too  much  satisfied  with  the  present,  and 
therefore  it  has  no  hope  to  urge  it  forward. 

Opposed  to  Optimism  is  Pessimism,  which  has  as  its 
moving  power  the  imperfection,  the  evil,  and  the  sin  which 
are  in  the  world.  Pessimism  assumes  tivo  forms.  It  may 
appear  in  a  more  passive  form,  and  then  it  leads  to  passive 
renunciation  of  moral  effort,  resignation,  melancholy  despair 
of  the  coming  of  the  chief  good.  This  is  moral  impotence, 
unbelief.  If  an  interest  is  still  taken  in  the  kingdom  of  God, 
yet  work  is  done  with  spiritless  hands  and  progress  is  made 
with  feeble  knees  (Heb.  xii.  12),  whereas  faith  demands  us 
^eeiv  TTveu/xari  (Rom.  xii.  11).  Here  too,  it  may  be,  instead 
of  honest  and  zealous  work,  there  is  the  expectation  of  extra- 
ordinary events  which  will  make  everything  turn  out  for  the 
best  •  (in  the  highest,  Christian  form  of  Pessimism,  it  is  the 
second  coming  of  Christ  that  is  expected)  ;  but  meanwhile  all 
moral  labour,  except  perhaps  what  is  expended  on  directly 
religious  objects,  is  regarded  as  vain,  futile,  or  even  sinful. 
Here  there  is  exhibited  a  sour,  censorious  disdain,  a  barren  and 
pernicious  mistrust. 

The  second  main  form  of  Pessimism  is  the  active.  Here  we 
find  a  restless  haste  which  will  not  enter  confidently  into  the 
present  and  the  work  of  God  that  is  in  it,  but  is  at  variance 
with  it,  and  thinks  to  reach  a  better  state  of  things  by  some 
abrupt  way,  by  the  use  of  force,  the  violation  of  rights,  or  by 
fanatical  means — in  short,  by  a  single  spring  as  it  were,  and 
so  by  breaking  off  in  revolutionary  fashion  from  the  past 
course  of  historical  development. 

Pessimism  of  both  kinds  proceeds  as  if  the  kingdom  of  God 
were  altogether  absent  and  had  yet  to  come.  According  to 
the  first  species  of  Pessimism,  its  coming  is  to  be  brought 
about  by  a  sudden  act  on  the  part  of  God,  which  must   be 


OF  PESSIMISM.       PESSIMISM  WITHIN  THE  CHURCH.  393 

passively  awaited, — tliis  is  the  position  of  the  Darbyitcs  with 
their  objective  chiliasm.  According  to  the  second,  it  is  to  be 
brought  about  by  human  intervention,  which  has  to  lay  the 
foundations,  alike  of  society,  the  State,  and  the  kingdom  of 
God,  entirely  by  human  effort,  or  which  at  least  has  to  prepare 
the  way  for  the  second  coming  of  our  Lord, — this  is  the  form 
in  which  Pessimism  has  been  held  by  many  parties  from 
the  Ancibaptists  of  the  Eeformation  time  onward. 

In  accordance  with  the  principle  on  which  it  rests. 
Pessimism  gives  rise  to  all  sorts  of  ideals,  set  up  by  fanaticism 
in  the  various  spheres  of  life, — especially  the  political  and 
educational, — such  as  the  dreams  of  comnnmism  and  socialism. 
In  the  ecclesiastical  sphere,  moreover,  we  find  all  kinds  of 
church-ideals :  that,  for  example,  of  Donatistic  purity,  either  in 
morality  or  in  piety  and  intelligence.  Here  we  find  separa- 
tion and  exclusion  advocated,  either  from  men  wishing  to 
form  a  Church  composed  of  the  regenerate  alone,  or  from  their 
demanding  perfect  purity  in  one  department  at  least — that  of 
public  instruction,  in  the  teachers  of  the  Church.  This  means 
a  pure  creed,  and  brings  us  back  to  the  demand  that  at  least 
the  clerical  order  shall  consist  of  the  regenerate  alone,  if  the 
Church  is  to  be  a  Church.  For  according  to  evangelical 
principles,  we  can  demand  a  creed  only  as  the  product  of 
evangelical  faith,  so  that  to  require  a  pure  creed  is  identical 
with  requiring  regenerating  faith.  Donatistic  Pessimism 
refuses  to  be  satisfied  with  a  lowly  condition  of  the  Church, 
in  which  it  includes  unbelievers  among  the  ministers  of  the 
word  as  well  as  among  its  members  at  large ;  it  seeks  by 
means  of  force  or  compulsion  to  rid  itself  of  such  as  are  not 
or  not  yet  at  one  with  the  Church  in  its  creed.  Of  course,  it 
cannot  hinder  hypocrisy,  but  may  very  readily  increase  it. 

Others,  instead  of  allying  themselves  with  the  beginnings  of 
the  kingdom  of  God  that  are  in  history  and  in  the  present, 
would  like  to  make  a  new  beginning,  to  bring  back  again, 
perhaps,  a  past  period  of  history,  such  as  that  of  primitive 
Christianity  or  of  the  Eeformation  time — the  Irvingitc  restora- 
tion of  the  apostolate  is  an  instance  in  point.  But  if  the  king- 
dom of  God  has  in  nowise  come  as  yet,  it  cannot  come  at  all, 
for  it  is  ethical,  and  can  therefore  be  established  only  in  an 
ethical  and  not  in  a  magical  way.     And  whatever  is  ethically 


394  §  47.    CHRISTIAN  VIEW  OF  THE  WOELD. 

produced  in  any  spliere  must  have  a  living  point  of  connection 
with  the  present.  In  Pessimism,  which  seeks  to  break  with 
the  past  and  present,  and  to  destro}^  them  in  order  to  intro- 
duce what  is  new,  there  is  something  dualistic,  something 
Manichsean,  just  as  in  the  premature  satisfaction  of  Optimism 
there  is  an  element  of  Pelagianism.  It  rends  asunder  the 
unity  and  continuity  of  the  world  as  a  whole,  since  it  opposes 
to  the  actually  existing  world  a  world  of  the  imagination  ;  and 
so,  wholly  unsatisfied  with  what  has  been,  it  loves  to  talk  of 
a  future  state,  a  future  Church,  a  future  religion.  It  may 
cherish  hope,  but  it  is  a  liopc  witliout  faith, — that  is,  it  is 
purely  subjective,  not  a  hope  that  is  the  outcome  of  the  past 
and  the  present,  of  faith  and  love.  Pessimism  is  restless 
haste  and  impatience  ;  not,  like  Optimism,  premature  rest  and 
contentment.  But  mere  restless  movement  results  only  in 
stagnation,  and  Pessimism,  however  hostile  it  is  to  all  con- 
servatism, never  makes  any  real  advance.  For,  in  accordance 
with  its  principle,  it  always  acts  abruptly  ;  it  is  continually 
starting  from  the  beginning  over  again,  and  thus  all  progress 
is  rendered  impossible,  and  a  perpetual  standstill  is  the  result. 
While  Pessimism  in  its  active  form  is  that  restless  haste 
which  never  makes  any  advance,  because  it  always  begins 
anew  and  breaks  with  what  has  hitherto  taken  place,  Optimism, 
on  its  side,  is  even  less  cafcthU  of  progress.  It  is  mere  immo- 
bility ;  it  lowers  its  ideal,  and  denies  the  imperfections  of  the 
present.  The  Xew  Testament  represents  the  kingdom  of  God 
on  the  one  side  as  already  come  for  faith,  and  on  the  other 
as  still  coming.^  But  this  ethically  necessary  association  of 
two  apparent  opposites  is  dissolved  both  by  Optimism  and 
Pessimism,  and  that  in  opposite  ways.  Optimism  holds  to 
the  first  alone,  to  the  fact  that  the  kingdom  of  God  has  come ; 
it  is  faith  without  hope  to  impel  it  forward,  since  it  has  no 
conception  of  the  richness  of  the  Christian  principle,  or  of  the 
far-reaching  moral  problems  which  the  latter  brings  to  view;  it 
is  therefore  faith  of  only  a  superficial  kind.  Pessimism,  on  the 
other  handjholds  to  the  second  alone, to  the  fact  that  the  kingdom 
of  Gocl  is  yet  to  come.      But  it  does  not  do  this  on  the  ground 

1  Luke  xvii.  20  ;  Matt.  xi.  12,  vi.  33  ;  John  iii.  3-5  ;  Matt.  xxv.  34  ;  cf. 
Matt.  vi.  10,  Th}'  kingdom  come.  Chap,  xiii.,  The  mustanl-seed.  1  Cor.  xv.  50  ; 
Kom.  xiv.  17. 


CHRISTIANITY  AND  THE  PAIN  OF  PESSIMISM.  395 

that  the  kingdom  has  already  come ;  and  so>  while  it  may 
have  a  higher  idea  of  the  problem  to  be  wrought  out  in  the 
conversion  of  the  world,  it  has  no  faith  in  the  power  of  grace 
that  is  already  in  the  world ;  its  hope  is  a  hope  without  faith, 
not  Christian  hope,  but  one  that  is  ever  ready  to  fall  back  into 
legalism. 

2.  Whereas  in  Christian  hope,  joy  {■^(apa.)  is  associated 
with  true  Xvirr]  (2  Cor.  vii.  10  ;  Col.  i.  24),  we  find  in 
Pessimism  and  Optimism  a  false  sadness  and  a  false  joy. 

{a)  The  pain  of  Pessimism  is  superficial,  as  is  seen  when 
we  consider  its  two  forms.  (a)  It  may  take  a  merely 
ocsthetic  or  eudaemonistic  form,  in  which  it  is  aroused  only  by 
the  physical  evils  that  exist,  or  by  the  lack  of  worldly  bless- 
ings ;  it  may  be  by  evils  that  affect  a  whole  community,  such 
as  the  failure  of  one's  country  to  secure  power  and  glory,  or 
the  want  of  external  splendour  in  the  condition  of  the  Church. 
The  last  of  these  plays  an  important  part  in  the  modern  forms 
of  cliiliasm,  e.g.  in  Darhyism  and  Irvingism,  where  pain  is 
chiefly  felt  at  the  imperfect  appearance  of  things.  (/8)  Again, 
the  pain  of  Pessimism  may  directly  refer  to  the  sin  of  the 
world,  its  might  and  dominion,  or  to  the  power  of  Satan  over 
the  world.  But  sin  is  here  taken  as  absolutely  unconquer- 
able, so  that  the  first  Parousia  of  Christ  is  unable  to  meet  it, 
and  only  the  power  of  His  second  coming  will  be  sufficient  to 
overcome  it.  In  the  meantime,  Pessimism  opposes  to  sin  no 
hearty  labour  of  love,  least  of  all  a  labour  undertaken  in 
common,  but  only  action  of  a  violent  kind,  for  the  most  part 
negative,  separatistic,  and  uninspiring ;  or  its  opposition  con- 
sists in  mere  passive  resignation,  at  most  in  bearing  a  Christian 
testimony  in  the  world.  Pessimism  doubts  the  possibility  of 
the  gospel  still  being  what  it  once  was — a  power  that  is 
able  to  overcome  every  form  of  individual  and  social  sin. 
Accompanying  this  renunciation  of  loving,  inspiring  activity, 
we  find,  as  a  matter  of  course,  that  the  Pessimist  regards 
himself  as  opposed  to  the  world,  which  he  looks  upon  as  lost, 
and  the  judgment  of  which  he  is  awaiting.  Nay,  he  even 
takes  pleasure  (Matt.  vii.  1)  in  assuming  the  office  of  judge, 
and  anticipating  the  verdict  of  God,  by  uncharitably  suppos- 
ing the  worst  of  every  one,  and  so  keeping  up  within  himself 
the  feeling  that  he  is  a  stranger  and  pilgrim  in  the  world.     It 


396     §  47.    CHRISTIAN  VIEW  OF  THE  WORLD.       CHRISTIANITY  AND 

naturally  follows  from  this,  that,  since  the  heart  is  concealed 
from  human  view,  a  tendency  is  manifested  to  devise  after  a 
legal  fashion  certain  tests,  by  which  the  Christianity  of  each 
one  may  be  gauged. 

Now  Christianity  deepens  the  pain  of  Pessimism.  If  the 
latter  appears  in  an  aesthetic  form,  then  Christianity  enlightens 
it  as  to  the  connection  that  exists  in  all  departments  of  life 
between  evil  and  sin,  and  also  between  Christianity  and  the 
highest  blessings.  Again,  if  the  pain  is  felt  with  reference  to  sin 
(a  legalistic  spirit  being  predominant),  then  Christianity  deepens 
it,  by  taking  the  man  who  has  set  himself  apart  as  a  judge, 
disclosing  to  him  the  sinfulness  of  the  uncharitableness  and 
pride  which  he  exhibits,  and  thus  surrendering  him  to  inward 
self-condemnation.  Christianity  takes  the  edge  off  pessimistic 
pain.  For  it  comes  to  him  who  so  willingly  finds  pleasure  in 
taking  up  the  role  of  an  accuser  or  judge,  or  who  would 
fain  play  the  part  of  a  misunderstood  benefactor  of  the  world, 
tells  him  that  his  true  position  is  one  of  humility,  and  exhorts 
him  before  everything  else  to  accuse  himself,  and  to  recognise 
the  connection  between  the  common  sin  of  humanity  and  his 
own  personal  share  in  it.  And  then  it  assures  him  that 
absolute  reconciliation  with  God  is  to  be  found  in  divine 
grace,  and,  by  reminding  him  of  what  a  load  of  guilt  has  been 
lifted  off  his  own  soul,  weans  him  from  his  spirit  of  exacting 
and  censorious  arrogance  towards  his  fellow-servants.  Further, 
since  in  absolute  reconciliation  with  God  we  are  already  made 
partakers  of  the  chief  good,  Christianity  takes  away  all  bitter- 
ness from  the  pain  that  is  felt  at  the  deficiencies  everywhere 
visible,  and  teaches  us  to  be  thankful  for  the  good  that  exists 
(Col.  i.  12),  and  to  cease  from  over-estimating  what  as  yet  is 
wanting.  Especially  does  it  teach  us  not  to  put  too  high  a 
value  upon  the  secondary  spheres,  as  if  in  these  by  themselves 
the  absolute  good  could  be  found.  It  therefore  gives  a  deeper 
ethical  character  to  the  dissatisfaction  of  Pessimism,  and  by 
this  means  paves  the  way  for  that  contentment  with  the  lead- 
ings of  Providence,  tliat  inner  peace  and  joy,  in  which  alone 
there  resides  the  power  to  yield  us  true  serenity  of  spirit  amid 
the  contradictions  of  the  world. 

(5)  Christianity,  too,  imparts  a  deeper  tone  to  the  joy  of 
Optimism.      It  brings   to   bear   upon   it   the    pain  which    is 


THE  JOY  OF  OPTIMISM.       CHRISTIAN  COURAGE.  397 

experienced  at  sin  both  within  and  without  ourselves,  and  so 
leads  us  to  find  joy  in  that  good  which  alone  is  worthy  of  the 
name, — a  good  which  now  exists,  but  which  no  less  ever 
points  us  to  a  future  that  demands  our  labour  in  the  present 
time.  Thus  Christianity  sets  both  Optimism  and  Pessimism 
right ;  in  these  the  human  spirit  is  at  a  false  point  of  view, 
and  Christianity  brings  it  back  to  the  true  one.  Christian 
faith  gives  it  its  true  starting-point,  and  Christian  hope  its  true 
goal.  The  joy  of  the  Christian  is  a  noble  joy.  Treading  the 
path  of  sorrow,  and  mortification  of  everything  that  is  impure, 
it  becomes  joy  in  the  possession  of  a  good  that  shall  never 
pass  away  (1  Pet.  i.  6,  ii.  19  f . ;  Jas.  i.  2  f.).  It  is  true  that 
this  joy  gives  rise  to  a  new  kind  of  sorrow,  viz.  to  compassion 
for  the  world  with  its  mistaken  ideas  of  happiness.  But  it 
is  not  a  sorrow  that  manifests  itself  in  cold  separatism  or  in 
stubborn  despondency ;  it  is  a  sorrow  that  carries  its  consola- 
tion in  itself,  that  enters  into  Christian  love,  inspires  it  with 
active  courage,  and  gives  it  vigour.  Thus  we  see  that 
Christian  hope,  since  it  tlow^s  out  of  faith  and  finds  an  outlet 
in  active  love,  is  opposed  to  both  the  extremes  which  have 
been  discussed.  And  so  what  has  already  been  said  is  once 
more  confirmed,  that  Christian  hope  contains  the  germs  or 
buds,  as  it  were,  of  the  Christian  spirit. 

3.  Christian  courage  (avSpela).  The  perversity  of  the 
world  is  often  so  overwhelming,  that  goodness  appears  to  be 
overborne  by  wickedness.  It  is  this  which  furnishes  materials 
for  tragedy,  and  these  are  to  be  found  not  only  in  poetry,  but 
often  enough  in  actual  life.  Now,  in  our  conflict  with  sin, 
both  within  and  witliout,  we  may  be  apt  to  regard  the  powers 
of  evil  as  too  strong  or  even  as  invincible.  And  this  is  the 
trial  of  our  faith ;  for  faith  cannot  remain  sound  if  its  hopes 
for  the  future  are  broken.  The  assurance  which  it  possesses 
wears  away  when  hope,  into  which  it  must  blossom,  gives 
place  to  despondency  and  cowardice.  At  such  a  time  it  is 
needful,  above  all  things,  that  the  foundation  be  renewed,  that 
is,  that  faith  again  be  made  strono;.  We  must  make  our- 
selves  clearly  conscious  of  the  fact  that  in  Christ  the  kingdom 
of  God  is  already  in  existence,  and  that  He  is  the  truth  and 
the  power  of  the  present.  Against  the  world  which  stands  in 
contradiction  to  Christianity,  that  world  which  spreads  around 


398  §  47.    CHRISTIAN  VIEW  OF  THE  WORLD. 

US,  and  yet  in  its  inner  nature  is  so  unsubstantial,  we  must 
bring  into  force  the  idealism  oi  faith,  or  faith  on  its  mystical 
side.  When  this  is  done,  then  to  faith  the  world,  so  far  as 
it  is  opposed  to  God,  ceases  to  exist:  faith  becomes  again 
assured  of  the  powerlessness  of  this  world  against  the  world 
so  far  as  it  is  in  harmony  with  God ;  for  apart  from  God  the 
world  has  only  a  semblance  of  life.  In  this  way  the  human 
spirit  again  enters  its  stronghold,  and  there  regains  its  freedom. 
To  it  the  power  of  sin  and  error  is  already  judged,  and  in  the 
growth  and  spread  of  wrong  it  sees  only  the  development  of 
evil  toward  certain  destruction.  The  bitterness  and  harsh- 
ness of  the  pain  that  is  felt  when  the  kingdom  of  God  in 
Christ  seems  itself  to  be  threatened,  disappear  when  we 
recognise  the  folly  and  vanity  of  all  attacks  that  are  made  on 
the  kingdom  of  God.  Nay,  when  the  Christian  has  recovered 
himself  in  faith,  he  sees  that  his  former  anxiety  about  the 
kingdom  of  God  was  itself  but  folly,  no  less  than  the  blindness 
displayed  in  assailing  it :  and  so  even  that  which  was  most 
terrifying  and  tragic  can  now  draw  forth  a  song  of  triumph 
such  as  Paul's,  "  0  death,  where  is  thy  sting  ?  0  grave, 
where  is  thy  victory  ?  Thanks  be  to  God  which  giveth  us 
the  victory,  through  our  Lord  Jesus  Christ ; "  or  the  words  of 
the  Psalmist,  "  Why  do  the  heathen  rage,"  etc.  (Ps.  ii.). 

Here  we  have  what  may  be  called  Christian  humotir}  But 
it  is  humour  of  a  high  and  Christian  kind,  only  when  the 
spiritual  serenity  that  has  been  rescued  out  of  the  confusions 
of  things  temporal  does  not  fall  into  Optimism  and  become, 
as  in  the  case  of  Friedr.  Schlegel,  an  irony  that  is  wholly 
indifferent  to  the  conflict  which  goes  on  in  the  world;  an 
irony  that  refuses  to  take  any  part  in  that  conflict,  either  in 
the  way  of  sympathy  or  of  action.  Whoever,  in  order  to 
maintain  a  mood  of  ostensible  superiority,  takes  only  a  bird's- 
eye  view,  as  it  were,  of  earthly  activity,  and  looks  upon  all 
that  men  busy  themselves  about  with  such  tragic  earnestness 
as  folly  and  vanity  and  so  as  a  kind  of  tragi-comedy, — such  a 
man  is  given  up  to  sensuous  egoism,  and  only  betrays  folly 
in  another  shape,  that,  namely,  of  frivolity  and  life-weariness. 
On  the  other  hand,  it  would  hardly  be  possible  to  find  a  wise, 
observant,  and  courageous  Christian,  who  has  not  again  and 
^  [Cf.  F.  J.  Meier's  address,  Htimor  mid  GhristentJmm.     1876.— Ed.] 


CHRISTIAN  HUMOUK.  399 

again  indulged  in  Christian  humour,  and  found  it  give  an 
impulse  and  zest  to  his  life.  It  is  wholly  justifiable  and  even 
a  duty,  especially  in  times  when  in  the  Church,  for  instance, 
or  in  any  other  community,  error  and  perversity  have  grown 
to  a  gigantic  height.  Then  the  conflict  which  we  carry  on 
would  lack  the  circumspection  and  courage  that  are  needful, 
did  we  not,  by  taking  a  true  Cluistian  view  of  things,  attain 
that  self-control  which  enables  us  to  apply  the  proper 
standard  to  the  appearance  of  power  possessed  by  opposing 
forces,  and  which  strengthens  our  joy  in  the  present  and  future 
kingdom  of  God.  But  Christian  humour  is  a  salt  in  our 
life,  not  only  when  we  are  opposing  hostile  powers,  but  also 
when  we  turn  to  ourselves,  for  it  serves  to  keep  us  from 
becoming  dull,  despondent,  and  slothful.  It  is  the  source  of 
that  speech  seasoned  v/ith  salt  which  is  so  pleasant  to  hear 
(Col,  iv.  6).  It  demands,  therefore  (and  this  is  a  test  of 
its  purity),  that  we  set  ourselves  not  only  against  the  per- 
versities that  we  see  around  us,  but  also  against  that  sinful 
reflex  of  them  which  is  in  ourselves,  which  consists  in 
despondency  and  fear  of  the  power  of  wickedness,  and  in 
an  exaggerated  estimate  of  that  power,  and  which  often 
expresses  itself  in  bitter  and  passionate  judgments  upon 
others. 

Further,  Christian  humour  must  be  accompanied  by  the 
most  living  interest  in  the  struggle  that  is  waged.  When 
this  is  the  case,  it  becomes  a  moving  power  in  that  spiritual 
serenity  which  inspires  the  Christian  with  the  bright  and 
joyful  hope  that  the  kingdom  of  God  will  prosper  even  by 
means  of  its  very  adversaries,  and  sends  him  forth  assured  of 
victory  and  prepared  anew  to  fight  and  to  conquer.  When 
the  Christian  has  retired  upon  himself  and  regained  his 
spiritual  energy,  the  sympathy  of  Christian  love  now  becomes 
the  means  of  bringing  him  out  once  more  into  the  sphere  of 
external  activity.  Since  Christian  humour  maintains  the 
liveliest  interest  in  the  good  and  its  realization,  it  cannot 
remain  shut  up  in  solitary  and  selfish  enjoyment.  It  cannot 
make  the  follies  and  perversities  of  the  world  the  material 
of  its  enjoyment,  or  a  background  to  it, — this  is  diabolical 
pleasure,  and  requires  the  continued  existence  of  evil.  On 
the  contrary,  as  soon  as  the  Clnistian  has  won  that  inward 


400  §  47.    CHRISTIAN  VIEW  OF  THE  WORLD. 

self-control  and  strength,  which  makes  the  opponents  of  the 
highest  good  seem  no  longer  dangerous,  there  arises  within 
him  the  feeling  of  compassion,  when  he  sees  how  men  are 
shut  out  from  the  highest  good  through  their  own  perversity. 
Thus  his  newly-won  sense  of  the  reality  of  the  chief  good  and 
of  its  worth  rouses  him  to  active  love.  Love,  however,  does 
not  treat  men  merely  as  objects  of  compassion,  as  suffering 
and  sick, — it  treats  them  in  accordance  with  their  idea,  as 
being  all  equals  and  free,  and  so  it  enters  upon  a  chivalrous 
conflict  with  wickedness  (Eph.  vi.  10  f.).  The  compassion 
of  the  Christian  is  not  a  mere  sentiment,  but  issues  in 
action,  when,  in  conformity  with  his  calling,  he  takes  up  the 
contest  with  wickedness,  and  makes  himself  the  organ  of  the 
<Tood  and  of  its  honour — militia  Christi.  But  whether  the 
duty  of  the  Christian  soldier  calls  him  to  suffer  or  to  act, 
the  ^^Xo?  which  inspires  him,  and  which  is  Christian  love, 
moves  him  all  the  while  (just  because  its  aim  is  the  good) 
to  love,  in  his  ideal  form,  the  man  whom  it  combats  as 
wicked. 

Christ  gives  us  an  example  of  the  courage  that  springs 
from  a  true  Christian  view  of  the  world.  At  the  lowest 
point  of  his  humiliation  He  acknowledges  freely  that  He  is  a 
king,  a  fact  which  at  other  times  He  concealed  (John  xviii. 
36  f. ;  cf.  vi.  15  ;  John  xvi.  33  ;  1  John  v.  1  ff.).  He  is  in 
heaven,  while  He  is  upon  earth  (John  iii.  13),  and  in  spirit 
He  sees  the  fruits  appearing  (John  iv.  35)  which,  neverthe- 
less, can  only  be  brought  forth  through  the  death  of  the  corn 
of  wheat  (John  xii.  24).  He  announces  His  final  victory, 
and  lets  the  world  recognise  in  Him  the  majesty  of  the 
world's  judge,  even  while  He  is  being  judged  Himself  and  led 
to  His  death.  But  this  conscious  dignity  in  which  He 
anticipates  His  triumph  does  not  estrange  Him  from  the 
world.  In  loving  sadness  He  gazes  upon  Jerusalem,  which 
is  about  to  reject  Him  (Matt,  xxiii.  37),  and  purifies  the 
temple,  while,  nevertheless,  He  predicts  its  approaching 
downfall.  His  grief  and  compassion  never  lose  their  practical 
energy.     "  Weep  not  for  me." 

4.  Hope,  thus  rooted  in  faith  and  united  with  love,  now 
makes  every  effort  of  the  Christian  fruitful  in  realizing  some 
portion  of  the  highest  good.     Christian  virtue  is  not  solicitous 


PKODUCTIYENESS  OF  CHRISTIAN  VIRTUE.  401 

about  results.  But  neither  is  it  indifferent  towards  them.  The 
opinion  is  often  held,  that  results  do  not  rest  in  the  hands  of 
man  at  all,  and  that  the  goodness  of  a  volition  must  not  be 
measured  by  the  result.  If  this  were  absolutely  true,  it  would 
mean  that  it  does  not  matter  what  we  purpose,  so  long  as  it 
arises  out  of  a  right  disposition.  But  if  no  good  comes 
of  an  act,  then  we  have  not  willed  the  right  thing,  and 
therefore  also  not  in  the  right  way — that  is  to  say,  we  have 
not  been  guided  by  the  virtue  of  Christian  wisdom.  What- 
ever is  willed  rightly  is  done  in  God  and  willed  by  God; 
and  when  this  is  the  case  beneficial  results  are  sure  to 
follow,  although  it  nevertheless  remains  true  that  the 
thoughts  of  man  and  of  God  in  nowise  coincide.  Only  we 
must  keep  this  fact  clearly  in  mind,  that  the  kingdom  of 
God  may  be  celebrating  its  triumphs  when  to  all  appear- 
ance it  is  suffering  defeat.  Accordingly,  the  Christian,  even 
when  he  is  apparently  unsuccessful,  does  not  move  in  uncer- 
tainty;  he  is  not  beating  the  air  (1  Cor.  ix.  26).  Christian 
virtue  does  not  consist  in  an  aimless  ijrogressus  in  infinitum, 
which  would  be  no  better  than  standing  still  or  revolving  in  a 
circle ;  on  the  contrary,  at  each  moment  it  attains  something, 
produces  either  inwardly  or  outwardly  some  portion  of  the 
highest  Good,  some  definite  result,  which  in  its  turn  yields 
fruit  in  the  future. 


SECOND    DIVISION. 

THE  SUBSISTENCE  OF  THE  CHRISTIAN  CHARACTER  BY  xMEANS  OF 
CONSTANT  RENEWAL  AND  EXERCISE. 

§48. 

The  self-maintenance,  of  the  Christian  personality,  which  is  the 
same  thing  as  its  growth,  gives  rise  to  a  new  series  of 
virtues.  It  is  realized  by  means  of  imrification,  and  also 
by  exercise,  which  becomes  expertness  in  virtue.  When 
faith,  love,  and  hope  become  aptitudes,  we  have  the  trinity 
of  fidelity,  stedfastness,  sober-mindedness.  Through  puri- 
2c 


•102        §  48.    SUBSISTENCE  OF  THE  CHKISTIAN  CHARACTER. 

fication  and  exercise,  however,  Christian  virtue,  although 
in  principle  a  perfect  \vhole,  enters  upon  a  process  of 
growth,  or  a  life  of  successive  stages,  in  which  it  is 
gradually  unfolded.  For  virtuous  aptitude  is  strength- 
ened only  when  an  ever  more  and  more  successful  course 
of  self-discipline  is  pursued,  and  when  at  the  same  time 
all  the  powers  of  our  nature,  spiritual  and  physical, 
those  which  are  the  same  in  all  and  those  which  are 
peculiar  to  the  individual,  are  taken  possession  of  or 
inspired  by  the  principle  of  Christian  virtue,  which  by 
this  means  gains  so  many  organs  and  capacities  for  its 
own  manifestation.  When  the  principle  of  virtue  has  thus 
put  its  stamp  upon  the  personality  of  the  individual  in 
all  the  manifold  variety  of  his  powers, — these  powers  all 
the  while  continuing  to  form  a  complete  and  harmonious 
unity  (a7rXoT779,  elXiKpiveta), — we  have  the  Christian 
character  in  the  stricter  sense  of  the  word. 

1.  Biblical  Doctrine.  The  new  personality  continues  as 
such  only  by  constantly  renewing  itself  (Col.  iii.  9  f. ;  Eph. 
iv.  24),  and  thus  accomplishing  its  work  of  self-sanctification. 
This  renewal  is  carried  out — («)  negatively,  by  a  process  of 
purification  (Kadapai'i)  (1  John  i.  9 ;  2  Cor.  vii.  1  ;  Eom. 
vi.  1  ff. ;  Col.  iii.  9  ;  Phil.  ii.  12  ;  Tit.  ii.  12),  the  putting  off 
of  the  old  man ;  and  (b)  positivcljj,  by  exercise  ('yvfj,vaaia) 
(1  John  iii.  7  ;  Heb.  v.  14,  xii.  11  ;  1  Cor.  ix.  24-27).  Both 
the  negative  and  the  positive  element  may  be  comprehended 
in  aaK7)(TL<;  (Acts  xxiv.  16).  The  N"ew  Testament  makes 
the  general  demand  that  the  Christian  "  a<^vi'C,uv  kavrbv " 
(1  John  iii.  3  ;  Jas.  iv.  8  ;  1  Pet.  i.  22) ;  this  is  "  sanctification," 
which  comprehends  both  the  negative  and  positive  element. 
It  demands  that  the  new  man  keep  himself  rrjpeiv  kavrov 
(1  John  V.  18),  that  he  be  renewed  dvaKaiva)ai<i,  avaveovadai, 
(Col.  iii.  10  ;  Eph.  iv.  23  ;  Rom.  xii.  2  ;  2  Cor.  iv.  16  ;  Tit. 
iii.  5),  that  he  grow  (Eph.  iv.  12);  and  it  represents  these  as 
the  work  of  the  Holy  Spirit  (1  Pet.  i.  2  ;  Phil.  i.  4-7  ;  2  Thess. 
ii.  16,  17),  but  also  as  an  end  and  task  for  the  personal  effort 
of  the  Christian  (1  Thess.  iv.  3,  7).     And  finally,  it  holds  out  to 


SELF- ACTIVITY  OF  THE  CHRISTIAN.  403 

the  Christian  increasing  proficiency  in  virtue,  ability  iKavoTrjq, 
as  the  fruit  of  his  eftbrts,  and  demands  that  he  acquire  it 
(Col.  i.  12  ;  2  Cor.  iii.  6).  The  power  of  virtue,  moreover, 
which  in  its  entirety  is  comprehended  in  faith,  hope,  and  love, 
now  comes  under  a  neiu  as'pcct,  when  virtue  becomes  ])rojidcnci! 
or  liahit.  Then  faith  becomes  fidelity,  that  to  which  the  IsTew 
Testament  sometimes  gives  the  name  ir'iari'^  again,  or  hoKifxiou 
TYj'i  TTiaTecof  (Jas.  i.  3  ;  1  Pet.  i.  7) ;  love  becomes  the  sted- 
fastness  of  the  good  will,  virofiovrj  (Eom.  v.  4,  ii.  7  ;  Luke  viii. 
15  ;  1  Tim.  vi.  11  ;  2  Tim.  iii.  10  ;  Tit.  ii.  2  ;  Jas.  i.  3,  4 ;  Rev. 
ii.  19,  xiv.  12)  ;  and  lastly,  wisdom,  when  it  becomes  a  habit, 
is  cr«<^/jocrw77, sober-mindedness  (1  Tim.  ii.  9-15  ;  Acts  xxvi.  25  ; 
<Tco(f)povi(T/ui6<i,  2  Tim.  i.  7 ;  (T03(ppoveiv,  Eom.  xii.  3  ;  1  Pet.  iv.  7). 
2.  With  the  new  nature  of  the  believer  a  divine  life  is 
incorporated  and  becomes  his  own,  and  this  new  life  he  must 
now  deal  with  as  with  the  gifts  of  the  first  creation,  which 
are  talents,  as  it  were,  entrusted  to  him  to  be  put  out  to 
interest ;  although  it  remains  true  that  it  is  only  through 
communion  with  the  same  Spirit  of  God  from  whom  he 
received  the  new  nature,  and  through  His  power,  that  it  can 
be  maintained.  But  the  believer  is  no  longer  merely  recep- 
tive, but  spontaneous,  free,  and  co-operative  in  its  maintenance. 
To  him  who  hath  shall  be  given  (Matt.  xiii.  12).  Synergism 
must  indeed  be  rejected  when  it  means  that  at  any  time,  and 
of  our  own  strength,  we  can  do  anything  that  is  good  apart 
from  God  altogether,  or  that  any  such  doing  of  ours  could 
even  partly  effect  our  justification.  But  it  must  be  accepted 
in  the  sense  that  man  is  not  destined  to  remain  a  mere  passive 
channel  for  the  divine  will  to  flow  through,  as  if  there  were 
here  only  isolated  divine  acts  which  created  no  new  per- 
sonality in  man  to  be  the  focus  of  a  higher  life.  ISTeither  can 
the  believer  be  kept  and  protected  by  any  absolute  decree ;  he 
must  determine  to  be  protected,  and  so  protect  himself.  In  the 
present  life  there  is  no  finished  state  of  grace  (2  Pet.  i.  10); 
each  state  constantly  gives  birth  to  another,  and  is  therefore  in 
constant  movement.  And  in  order  that  this  process  of  repro- 
duction may  be  firmly  maintained,  it  is  necessary  that  there 
be  no  want  of  vigour  in  waging  war  with  present  evils,  but 
that  disorders  and  failings  be  at  once  taken  by  the  conscience 
of  the  Christian  as  signs  which  tell  from  what  side  the  power 


404        §  48.    SUBSISTENCE  OF  THE  CHEISTIAN  CHARACTER. 

of  the  enemy  is  threatening,  and  that  these  signs  be  taken  by 
his  will  as  a  real  summons  to,  a  real  conflict.  Here  there  are 
two  points  to  be  noticed. 

(a)  The  new  man  is  at  first  still  vrjirio'^,  and  has  to  grow  up 
unto  rfkiKia  XpiaTov  (Eph.  iv.  1 3).  He  is  feeble  and  unprac- 
tised, although  there  exists  in  the  centre  of  the  Ego  a  real 
blending  of  divine  and  human  life. 

(6)  The  new  personality  of  the  Christian  is  in  the  old,  which 
is  accustomed  to  devote  itself  and  its  powers  to  the  service  of 
another  principle  ;  and  thus  the  enemy  has  still  dominion  over 
a  portion  of  that  which  belongs  to  the  unity  of  the  personal 
life.  Now,  since  the  Christian  is  determined  by  whatever 
determines  him  on  either  side,  the  bad  as  well  as  the  good,  he 
can  assert  himself  as  a  new  man,  in  spite  of  this  persistent 
complication  with  sin,  only  by  showing  that  he  suffers 
unwillingly  the  impure  influences  that  affect  him,  and  so  is 
foreign  to  them  in  his  inmost  nature  ;  by  setting  his  will  in  con- 
scious opposition  to  them,  and  casting  them  off  by  an  inward 
process  of  disseverance  from  them,  which  always  goes  deeper 
and  deeper  and  costs  him  painful  self-denial.  The  new  per- 
sonality, in  which  sin  has  lost  its  power,  can  show  resistance 
to  the  sin  of  the  old  nature  that  still  cleaves  to  it,  only  by 
opposing  and  weakening  temptations  through  self-discipline ; 
and  this  discipline  must  be  pursued  in  such  a  way  that  as 
the  new  personality  grows  stronger  it  ever  continues  to  sub- 
jugate new  portions  of  that  region  from  which  temptations 
arise,  and  to  make  them  living  organs  of  the  Good.  There  is 
no  vacuum  in  the  personal  life.  Whatever  part  of  it  remains 
unsubdued  by  the  new  man  finds  a  master  for  itself,  or  rather, 
it  keeps  the  old  one,  who  does  not  abdicate  of  his  own  accord. 
There  is  the  closest  connection  between  the  subsistence  of  the 
new  life  and  the  death  of  the  old,  between  the  preservation  of 
faith,  love,  and  hope  on  the  one  hand,  and  Christian  purifi- 
cation and  self-discipline  on  the  other,  and  it  is  by  means 
of  this  connection  that  growth  is  maintained.  The  new  man 
can  only  live  at  the  cost  of  the  old. 

Accordingly,  (a)  with  regard  to  the  maintenance  of  the  new 
man,  it  cannot  take  place  unless  we  engage  in  a  warfare  with 
the  evil  that  is  in  us.  It  is  a  dangerous  illusion  to  regard  the 
state  of  grace  as  a  state  of  rest ;  for  sin  does  not  and  cannot 


MAINTENANCE  AND  GROWTH.       ASCETICS.  405 

remain  at  peace  (Gal.  v.  17).  Peace  without  conflict  there- 
fore would  be  overthrow,  a  surrender  to  evil.  The  strife 
ceases  only  with  the  death  of  the  one  combatant  or  the  other. 
(^)  Likewise,  the  groivth  or  strengthening  of  the  new  man 
can  only  take  place  at  the  cost  of  the  old,  that  is,  by  the 
powers  which  were  in  the  service  of  the  latter  being  made 
organs  of  the  new  man  (Eora.  vi.  15-22).  And  finally,  (7) 
growth  and  maintenance  are  combined  in  the  closest  way.  For 
it  is  self-evident  that  there  can  be  no  growth  without  main- 
tenance. Inversely,  self-maintenance  in  the  form  of  exercise 
of  our  powers,  as,  for  instance,  in  conflict  with  sin,  tends  to 
strengthen  them.  Continued  purification  and  exercise  result 
not  only  in  daily  renewal  of  our  inmost  spirit,  but  also  in 
growth,  which  ensues  as  virtue  becomes  habitual.  Growth 
consists  in  this,  that  the  old  nature,  which  not  only  has 
never  hitherto  been  taken  possession  of  by  the  new  person, 
but  has  been  under  the  sway  of  ungodly  and  unregulated 
propensities,  is  more  and  more  made  subject  to  the  new  person 
and  becomes  its  willing  organ.  By  this  means  virtue  becomes 
habit  and  a  second  nature,  and  takes  the  forms  of  fidelity, 
stcdfastness,  sober -mindcdiiess  [cf.  §  43,  2,  p.  362. — Ed.]. 
Even  involuntarily  also  the  maintenance  of  the  new  per- 
sonality becomes  its  growth.  For  the  spiritual  vitality  it 
possesses,  acting  from  within  outwards,  impels  it  to  develop 
all  its  individual  powers  ;  while  it  is  continually  being  en- 
riched by  its  assimilation  of  something  new,  derived  from  the 
world,  from  God,  from  increasing  self-knowledge,  etc.  But  of 
this  we  shall  treat  farther  on. 

3.  Ascetics  is  the  doctrine  of  the  2^urification,  'pj^escrvation, 
and  strengthening  of  the  spiritual  life}  Since  faith,  love,  and 
hope  constitute  Christian  virtue  in  its  totality,  any  system  of 
purification  adopted  for  the  purpose  of  preserving  and  exercis- 
ing the  new  life  must  be  related  to  all  the  three ;  for  none  of 
them  can  be  healthy  apart  from  the  others.  Now  any  one  of 
these  virtues  may,  of  course,  be  specially  weak  and  imperilled ; 

^  Literature  :  Ktinhard,  I.e.  iv.  §  416-v.  §  478.  Schmid,  I.e.  pp.  63  sq., 
589-615.  Sclileiermacher,  Christl.  Sitte,  p.  141  sq.  Grundlinien  einer  Kritik 
der  hisherigen  Sittenlehre,  307  sq.  Eothe,  I.e.,  1st  ed.  vol.  iii.  §  869-873, 
878-894.  Martensen,  I.e.  ii.  1,  p.  485  sq.  Zockler,  Kritische  Geschichte  der 
Askese,  1863. 


406         §  48.    SUBSISTENCE  OF  THE  CHEISTIAA^  CIIARACTER. 

but  it  is  specially  important  that  the  life  of  faith  be  strength- 
ened, because  the  impulsive  power  of  the  whole  life  pro- 
ceeds from  it,  and  it  alone  makes  possible  a  progress  which  is 
real  growth,  and  not  merely  something  acquired  by  external 
practice.  It  is  important  above  everything  else  that  fellow- 
ship with  God  in  Christ  through  the  Holy  Spirit,  which  has 
been  checked  by  the  impurity  of  sin,  be  re-established  by 
means  of  a  course  of  conduct  chiefly  of  a  purifying  kind.  But 
now  the  question  arises :  when  we  engage  in  self-purification, 
in  order  to  subdue  the  predominance  of  the  life  of  sense,  are 
we  at  liberty  to  impose  upon  ourselves  privation,  abstinence, 
seclusion,  vigils,  sparing  enjoyment  of  food  and  drink,  in 
short,  fasting  of  every  sort,  whatever  is  comprised  in  so-called 
negative  Asceticism  ?-  And  then,  with  reference  to  positive 
exercise, — ought  there  to  be  actions  in  which  exercise  is  the 
sole  aim,  or  ought  exercise  only  to  take  such  forms  as  are  of 
moral  worth  in  themselves,  and  consequently  be  always  allied 
with  moral  production  ? 

]\Iany  distorted  ideas  have  crept  into  the  Roman  and  Greek 
Chiircli  with  reference  to  asceticism,  so  that  the  very  word 
has  almost  an  evil  ring  in  it.  Here  renunciations  and  self- 
tortures,  voluntarily  imposed  or  taken  upon  oneself,  are 
accounted  good,  meritorious  works  and  a  proof  of  virtue, 
while  no  attention  is  paid  to  the  motive  and  disposition  which 
prompted  them.  As  if  mere  abstinence  from  enjoyment,  from 
the  possession  of  property,  from  marriage,  or  the  undergoing 
of  pain  were  in  itself  something  well-pleasing  to  God,  although 
such  abstinence  or  suffering  does  no  good  to  any  one  !  This 
would  only  be  the  case  if  these  temporal  blessings  or  relations 
were  evil  in  themselves,  or  if  God  took  pleasure  in  the  pain  of 
the  creature  for  its  own  sake; — and  this  would  be  Manicheeism. 
The  "  stylites  "  of  the  Greek  Church  and  the  ascetics  of  the 
Roman  have  performed  wonders  in  the  way  of  exercises  of 
this  kind,  and  after  the  fashion  of  athletes  have  gained  admir- 
ing spectators.  It  is  clear  that  anything  of  this  sort  is 
reprehensible,  which  is  of  no  moral  assistance  to  the  man 
himself  and  is  of  no  use  to  others.  Such  pretended  saints,  in 
all  that  they  do,  are  not  in  the  least  occupied  with  the  realiza- 
tion of  any  good  aim,  they  do  not  have  any  good  end  in  view 
which  they  mean  to    attain  when    they  have  trained  their 


PERMISSIBILITY  OF  ASCETICISM.  407 

bodies  to  be  serviceable  iustruments  ;  on  the  contrary,  they 
injure  the  body,  and  set  up  the  mere  formal  display  of 
power,  either  of  a  negative  or  positive  kind,  as  in  itseK  a 
good  work  or  an  end  in  itself. 

But  while  such  asceticism  is  reprehensible,  the  question 
is  not  yet  settled  whether  asceticism  is  morally  permissible. 
Schleiermacher,^  Marteusen,"  and  Eothe  ^  call  attention  to  the 
following  considerations  against  it. 

(1.)  An  action  is  morally  good  when  in  it  the  good  as  a 
wdiole  is  willed,  as  well  as  some  particular  good ;  and  con- 
sequently it  must  involve  a  reference  to  the  common  aim  of 
all  moral  action,  the  realization  of  the  objective  supreme 
Good  in  the  world.  Hence  —  it  is  urged  —  action  of  an 
ascetic  nature,  since  it  is  directed  merely  to  the  moral  per- 
fecting of  oneself,  is  morally  blameworthy.  But  it  is  quite 
conceivable  that  asceticism  may  be  practised  for  the  pur- 
pose of  self-improvement,  because  the  latter  is  held  to  be  the 
necessary  preparation  for  working  in  the  best  interests  of  tlie 
whole.     These  two  things  are  quite  reconcilable. 

(2.)  The  second  question  is  of  more  importance  :  Can  the 
practice  of  asceticism  actually  promote  one's  moral  improve- 
ment ?  Are  we  at  liberty  to  recommend  that  by  means  of 
asceticism  a  supply  of  moral  force  should  be  stored  up,  to  be 
afterwards  used  with  vigour  in  the  concrete  relations  of  life, 
just  as  a  soldier  has  to  learn  his  drill,  certain  formal  acts  and 
movements,  in  order  to  prepare  him  for  war  ?  May  we  per- 
form actions  whose  value  is  entirely  formal,  in  order  to  learn 
to  act  with  full  moral  power  ?  Is  not  such  power  only  to  be 
gained  by  means  of  acts  that  have  aims  of  a  real  and  not  a 
formal  kind  as  their  contents,  just  as  we  can  only  learn  to 
swim  by  going  into  the  water  ;  and  is  it  not  therefore  the 
case  that  we  only  come  to  act  morally  by  practice  in  a  moral 
element,  namely,  in  the  spheres  of  actual  life  ?  It  is  certainly 
true  that  action  which  effects  absolutely  nothing,  or  is  purely 
formal,  is  not  moral  action.  But  one's  own  person  is  such  an 
element  as  we  have  spoken  of,  and  here  it  is  requisite  that 
labour  be  expended,  though  not  without  regard  to  the  Good 

^  Kritih  der  Stttenlehre,  p.  307  sq. 

^  System  der  Moralphilosophk,  p.  74  ;  I.e.  ii.  1,  p.  485. 

^  I.e.  iii.  p.  113. 


408        §  48.    SUBSISTENCE  OF  THE  CHKISTIAN  CHARACTEE. 

in  general.  It  is  at  least  certain,  that  no  one  can  accom- 
plish anything  for  the  good  of  others  until  he  possesses 
virtuous  energy  in  himself.  Thus  we  see  that,  in  accordance 
with  the  right  moral  order  of  duties,  each  one  should  first  of 
all  attend  to  the  strength  of  virtue  in  himself.  And  here 
even  abstinences  and  practices  that  are  self-imposed  have 
their  moral  right,  for  through  them  the  superiority  of  the  flesh 
is  broken,  and  temperance  and  sober-mindedness  are  secured. 
Without  these,  faith  is  impossible,  and  if  faith  were  gone  there 
could  be  no  origination  on  the  part  of  man,  flowing  from  the 
living  fountain  of  his  virtuous  energy.^  While  we  are  minors 
we  must  undergo  training  of  every  kind. 

But  we  have  still  to  distinguish  between  the  asceticism 
which  is  permissible  in  the  life  hefore  faith,  and  that  which 
peculiarly  belongs  to  the  Christian  life  as  such.  Previous  to 
faith,  ascetic  practice  cannot  be  the  outcome  of  the  power  of 
Christian  virtue ;  but  it  may  be  the  outcome  of  a  longing 
for  it,  and  so  its  aim  must  be  to  remove  everything  that 
stands  in  the  way  of  faith  and  of  the  birth  of  the  new 
man.  Tor  this  end,  still  self-communinfr  self-knowledcre,  and 
temperance  are  means  to  be  employed.  Hence  abstinence 
societies  are  quite  legitimate,  in  which  those  members  who 
have  greater  moral  strength  impose  restraints  upon  themselves 
for  the  sake  of  other  weaker  ones,  in  order  that  by  such 
fellowship  the  latter  may  be  led  to  self-discipline. 

In  the  case  of  Christians,  on  the  other  hand,  everything — 
fasting  of  every  kind  included — must  proceed  from  faith, 
from  the  pleasure  that  is  taken  in  the  growth  of  the  new 
man  (for  whose  sake  hindrances  are  taken  out  of  the  M-ay), 
from  the  desire  for  spiritual  increase  (Matt.  vi.  16  f.),  and 
from    the    dissatisfaction    that   the   Christian  feels  with  the 

^  Accordingly,  we  agree  with  Eothe  in  the  following  particulars.  On  the 
one  side,  he  rejects  that  asceticism  which  is  nothing  but  ascetic,  that  is  to 
say,  whicli  is  exclusively  taken  up  with  the  individual  self  ;  but,  on  the  other 
side,  he  acknowledges  that  asceticism  to  be  good  and  moral  which  diffuses 
itself  throughout  the  whole  of  the  moral  life,  as  long  as  the  latter  has  not 
arrived  at  its  full  power.  It  follows  as  a  matter  of  course,  that  when  those 
discords  in  the  individual  have  been  overcome,  which  asceticism  was  meant  to 
bring  to  an  end,  there  remains  no  further  need  for  it.  It  likewise  follows 
that  the  moral  necessity  for  asceticism,  which  exists  in  this  life,  is  matter 
for  humility,  so  that  asceticism  can  never  become  the  subject  of  ostentation 
nor  the  ground  of  meritoriousness  (cf.  iii.  pp.  114-117). 


MEANS  OF  VIRTUE.  409 

humiliating  want  of  freedom  which  he  still  experiences. 
Tasting  of  this  sort  is  no  mere  sadness  of  countenance ;  it 
is  a  manifestation  of  freedom  and  of  the  pleasure  that  is 
felt  in  the  new  life :  it  does  not  arise  from  pride  or  vanity, 
but  always  contains  something  that  is  humbling,  the  sense, 
namely,  that  it  is  still  required.  But  at  the  same  time  it  is 
productive,  for  it  promotes  the  freedom  of  the  Christian ;  and, 
because  it  is  a  strengthening  of  the  moral  spirit,  it  is  an 
increase  of  moral  good  which  will  yet  become  of  general 
benefit.  Such  asceticism — springing  as  it  does  from  the 
virtuous  energy  of  the  Christian,  which  is  ever  desirous  of 
growth — also  has  in  itself  a  standard  to  oppose  to  subversive 
extravagances  of  every  kind.  For  while  it  is  the  aim  of 
the  Christian  to  overcome  those  habits  and  tendencies  in 
his  natural  energies  which  are  opposed  to  his  spiritual  life, 
he  seeks  all  the  while  to  take  these  energies  themselves  and 
preserve  them,  by  making  them  the  organs  of  his  Christian 
freedom.^ 

4.  Means  of  Virtue.  Since,  in  accordance  with  what  has 
been  said,  even  mature  Christians  may  and  ought  to  practise 
asceticism,  we  have  now  to  inquire  as  to  the  measures  or 
means  ^  to  be  employed,  in  order  to  bring  to  a  successful 
issue  that  process  of  self-training  (in  the  way  of  purification 
and  exercise)  by  which  the  Christian  develops  his  virtuous 
energy  to  its  full  extent.  This  is  the  doctrine  of  the  means 
of  virtue,  which  has,  indeed,  been  often  stated  in  such  a  way 
as  to  split  up  the  unity  of  virtue,  or  make  of  it  a  mere 
patchwork,  and  consequently  to  give  countenance  to  the 
spirit  of  legalism.  The  means  of  virtue  are  the  ethical 
correlate  of  the  means  of  grace,  with  which  they  stand  in 
close  connection.  Means  of  virtue  are  acts  of  man,  means 
of  grace  are  aets  of  God.  The  former  are  such  acts  as  have 
for  their  aim  the  promotion  of  personal  virtue.  Strictly 
speaking,  to  the  Chris'tian  all  the  relations  of  life,  suffering 
included,  and  especially  his  vocation  and  private  relations, 
must  be  means  of  grace.      Nevertheless  there  are  also  special 

^  [It  is  self-evident  that,  in  the  author's  opinion,  the  manner  and  measure  of 
ascetic,  practice  must  be  left  to  the  judgment  of  the  individual  conscience. — Ed.] 

2  Cf.  Rothe,  1st  ed.  iii.  p.  120  scj.  §  878-894.  Reinhard,  vol.  iv.  §  416  to 
vol.  V.  §  478. 


410         §  48.    SUBSISTENCE  OF  THE  CHRISTIAN  CHARACTER. 

arrangements,  partly  in  existence  already,  partly  to  be  found 
out  by  the  Christian  himself,  which  serve  to  strengthen 
virtue.  Eenewal,  by  means  of  which  virtue  is  maintained 
and  grows,  is  partly  negative — purification,  partly  positive 
— exercise  (§  48,  2).  It  embraces  primarily  the  maintenance 
and  strengthening  of  faith,  but  it  also  includes  the  invigorat- 
ing of  the  intellect  and  the  will.  Now  a  course  of  purification 
and  exercise  which  has  faith  as  its  object  demands  the  so- 
called  religious  means  of  virtue ;  while  those  means  of  virtue 
which  are  directed  to  the  purification  and  strengthening  of 
the  intellect  and  the  will,  may  be  characterized  as  moral  in 
the  narrower  sense  of  the  word. 

{a)  Eeligious  oneans  of  virtue.  To  these  belong  prayer, 
contemplation,  use  of  the  word  of  God,  and  sacrament,  and 
also  association  Math  the  Christian  community  in  which  these 
are  the  ruling  standard.  All  these,  while  they  have  a  religious 
effect  in  the  way  of  purifying  and  training  the  Christian,  not 
only  benefit  faith,  but  also  do  good  to  the  intellect  and  the 
will. 

(h)  Moral  means  of  virtue.  To  these  belong:  (a)  so  far 
as  purification  is  concerned,  self-examination  on  the  side  of 
the  intellect  (1  Cor.  xi.  28),  dcnOi  penitential  discipline  on  the 
side  of  the  will.  In  self-examination,  calm  introspection, 
in  the  light  of  God's  word  and  in  solitude,  holds  the  most 
important  place ;  while  penitential  discipline  consists  chiefly 
in  fighting  against  the  predominant  influence  of  the  carnal 
nature,  and  in  humbling  ourselves  before  God,  also  before 
our  neighbour  should  circumstances  require. 

{jB)  The  positive  culture  and  increase  of  knowledge  or  of 
Christian  ivisdorn  are  gained  principally  through  our  contem- 
plating the  image  of  Christ  as  our  ideal;  but  it  is  also  of 
service  to  have  intercourse  with  rich  spiritual  minds  in 
literature  or  in  life.  Further,  we  acquire  virtuous  habits  of 
will,  or  of  love,  partly  by  learning  perfect  self-command  (so 
that  our  sensuous  nature,  in  particular,  is  always  becoming  a 
more  pliable  organ  for  the  spirit  of  love  that  is  in  us),  and 
partly  by  accustoming  ^  ourselves  to  forget  and  sacrifice  our- 
selves, and  to  open  up  our  heart  and  mind  more  and  more 
in  love  towards  others.  Finally,  it  is  requisite  that  we 
^  Giving,  for  example,  must  be  learned  by  practising  giring. 


vows.  411 

appoint  for  ourselves  a  regular  order  of  life  and  division  of 
time — and  here  our  choice  of  associates  takes  an  important 
place — -in  order  to  afford  full  satisfaction  to  all  that  is  required 
for  our  purification  and  growth.  Further  particulars  may  be 
deferred  to  the  next  division,  in  which,  as  we  have  now  spoken 
of  the  origin  and  subsistence  of  the  new  personality,  we  shall 
treat  of  its  self-manifestation  and  self-development.  For  the 
outward  activity  also  of  the  Christian  must,  as  we  have  seen, 
iioiu  from  the  principle  of  virtite  implanted  within  him,  and 
must  therefore  be  a  self-manifestation  and  self-development. 

Note. — Are  vows,  too,  means  of  ^'irtue  '.  From  what  has 
already  been  said,  it  follows  that  all  vows  are  reprehensible 
which  result  in  an  arbitrary  imposition  of  laws  upon  ourselves. 
All  tlie  powers  that  we  possess  belong  to  the  Lord,  and  we 
may  not  arbitrarily  dispose  of  them  for  the  sake  of  a  vow  which 
has  no  moral  necessity  in  it ;  for  we  are  not  our  own.  The 
law,  which  is  the  will  of  God,  lays  claim  to  the  whole  life  ;  and 
this  condemns  monastic  vows,  pilgrimages,  vows  concerning 
almsgiving,  mortification,  and  whatever  is  akin  to  these.  But 
is  it  in  all  cases  reprehensible  to  make  a  vow  ?  such  a  vow, 
for  instance,  as  to  be  obedient  to  something  which  is  really 
God's  will  ?  It  has  been  held  that  even  here  a  vow  is  irreligious, 
because  it  makes  it  apj^ear  as  if  apart  from  the  vow  we  were 
not  bound  to  obey  the  divine  will,  and  therefore,  as  if  that 
which  is  God's  will  had  no  binding  power  until  our  promise 
was  made.  Or  else — it  is  urged — a  vow  makes  it  appear  as 
if  it  were  entirely  within  the  free  power  of  man  to  fulfil  the 
commandment,  as  if  he  were  not  dependent  upon  God's  grace 
to  enable  him  to  do  so.  Now  where  the  one  or  the  other  of 
these  is  the  case,  a  vow  is  no  doubt  repreliensible,  but  such 
errors  are  by  no  means  necessarily  connected  with  vows. 
Vows  only  presuppose  that  man  can  refuse  to  acknowledge 
even  that  which  is  morally  incumbent  on  him ;  that,  while  God 
is  always  ready  to  help  a  sincere  will,  man  may,  on  the  one  hand, 
refuse  to  do  a  certain  duty,  or,  on  the  other,  may  make  up  his 
mind  to  be  obedient  to  God.  Hence  a  vow  simply  means  that 
he  fixes  this  resolution,  and  enforces  it  upon  himself,  as  the 
aim  of  his  future  unremitting  efforts.  Thus  making  a  vow 
is  closely  connected  with  faith  \_"  Gelolen"  and  "  Glauhen"], 
Unless  it  were  morally  permissible  to  make  such  a  vow  as  this, 
which  is  identical  with  the  resolve  to  lead  a  better  life,  we 
should  be  landed  in  ethical  Quietism,  and  man's  share  in  the 
work  of  his  own  moral  culture  denied.  It  follows,  however, 
from  what  has  just  been  said,  that,  strictly  speaking,  there  is 


412     §  49.    SELF-MANIFESTATIOX  OF  THE  CHEISTIAN  CHARACTER. 

only  071C  vow,  a  vow  referrini:^-  to  the  whole  life  and  corre- 
sponding to  the  one  all-embracing  covenant  M'hicli  faith  makes 
with  Christ  in  baptism.  This  one  life-vow  of  fidelity  to  Christ 
{confirmation)  comprehends  everything.  Vows  which  cannot 
find  a  place  in  it  are  not  allowable,  and  especially  a  vow  that 
involves  something  which  is  not  a  duty,  but  merely  a  project 
that  can  only  be  carried  out  at  the  cost  of  actually  existing 
duties. 


THIED  SECTION". 

THE  SELF-MANIFESTATION  OR  SELF-DEVELOPMENT  OF  THE 
CHRISTIAN  CHARACTER. 

§49. 

The  new  personality  is  even  in  itself  a  part  of  the  highest 
good,  by  reason  of  its  inherent  filial  relationship  to 
God,  and  it  is  so  not  merely  on  the  ground  of  the 
enjoyment  and  blessedness  which  it  involves,  but  because 
in  its  very  essence  and  being  it  is  thoroughly  good  and 
pure.  And  more  than  this ;  each  separate  person- 
ality, as  Christian,  is  a  good  of  an  individual  kind, 
for  the  natural  individuality  of  each  is  sanctified  and 
brought  to  pure  and  vigorous  maturity.  There  are  as 
many  Christian  characters  as  there  are  Christian  per- 
sons. But  the  Christian  personality  is  a  good  only 
because,  by  acting  out  its  own  inner  life,  and  thus  mani- 
festing what  it  is,  it  is  constantly  engaged  in  the  work 
of  increasing  the  highest  good. 

Chapter  First.     The  IVIanifestation  of  the  Godlike  Person- 
ality in  its  Absolute  Eelation. 
Chapter  Second.  In  Eelation  to  Itself. 
Chapter  Third.     In  Eelation  to  Others.^ 

1  [With  reference  to  this  division  the  following  remarks  may  be  made : — 
(1)  According  to  the  author's  view,  the  doctrine  of  the  Christian  jjersonality  is  by 
no  means  a  mere  doctrine  of  virtue  ;  the  personality  is  itself  also  a  part  of  the 
supreme  good,  and  shows  itself  in  the  acts  and  works  which  duty  demands. 
Hence  the  latter  are  spoken  of  as  the  outward  manifestation  of  the  person- 


§  50.    THE  CHRISTIAN  PERSONALITY  AS  EVINCING  PIETY.       413 


CHAPTEE  FIEST. 

THE  GODLIKE  PERSONALITY  IN  ITS   ABSOLUTE    RELATION  ;    OR   THE 
CHRISTIAN  PERSONALITY  AS  EVINCING  PIETY. 

§  50. 

A. — Christian  Piety  in  itself. 

Christian  piety  is  the  immediate  activity  in  which  is  embodied 
the  filial  relation  towards  the  Triune  God.  Eooted  in 
faith,  it  is  full  of  joyful  thankfulness  for  the  salvation 
that  has  been  experienced ;  in  the  presence  of  affliction 
and  sin  it  is  at  once  trustful,  courageous,  and  humble. 
And  having  regard,  not  merely  to  God's  gifts,  but  also 
directly  to  God  Himself,  it  is  the  loving  response  of  a 
child  to  the  fatherly  love  of  God.  Nor  does  the  child 
ever  forget  reverential  fear,  which,  on  the  contrary, 
increases  with  every  advance  in  the  knowledge  of  the 
deep  things  of  God,  of  His  majesty  and  love. 

[The  Literature.— Eothe,  1st  ed.  iii.  §  987-999.] 

1.  The  object  of  the  Christian's  love  is  God  in  Christ,  God 
Himself,  and  not  merely  His  gifts,  Matt.  xxii.  40  ;  1  John 
iv.  19;  Col.  iii.  17;  1  John  ii.  5,  15;  Jas.  iv.  4,  8;  cf. 
Deut.  vi.  5.  From  passages  such  as  Matt.  xxv.  40,  according 
to  which  we  ought  to  love  Christ  in  our  brethren,  it  does  not 
follow,  as  some  think,  that  we  can  or  ought  to  love  the  Head 
in  the  members  only,  and  to  love  God  in  men  only.  God  is 
also  a  personal  being  in  and  by  Himself,  and  we  can  enter 
into  moral  relationship  wdth  Him.     Love  to  God  and  love  to 

ality.  (2)  In  all  its  activities  the  Christian  personality  is  a  unity  ;  and  there- 
fore faith,  love,  and  ■wisdom  (fidelity,  stedfastness,  and  sober-mindedness)  are 
operative  throughout  them  all.  (3)  The  self-manifestation  of  the  personality, 
or  the  active  energy  it  displays,  is  divided  according  to  the  objects  to  which  it 
is  directed,  because  here  we  are  dealing  not  merely  with  a  doctrine  of  virtue,  but 
with  the  personality  as  engaged  and  manifested  in  the  performance  of  acts  of 
duty  and  the  production  of  external  works.  Hence  the  author  is  occupied 
with  a  complete  delineation  of  the  personality,  in  which,  as  Christian,  virtue, 
duty,  and  good  are  already  naturally  united. — Ed.] 


414       §  50.    THE  CHKISTIAN  PEESONALITY  AS  EVINCING  PIETY. 

man,  while  in  themselves  inseparable,  are  nevertheless  distinct, 
1  John  iv.  20  ;  cf.  iv.  9,  10.  Further,  when  it  is  treated  as 
idolatry  to  pay  divine  honours  to  Christ^  something  is  imputed 
to  Christianity  from  which  it  knows  itself  to  be  free,  viz. 
polytheism.  At  the  same  time,  it  is  certainly  true  that  the 
Church  regards  Christ  as  Eedeemer  and  Mediator  because  He 
is  the  revelation  of  the  personal  love  of  God,  not  only  the 
way,  but  also  the  truth  and  the  life ;  not  a  mediator  who 
separates  us  from  God,  but  rather  one  in  whom  is  God  Him- 
self ;  so  that  we  see  and  find  the  Father  in  the  Son,  who  is 
the  absolute  image  of  the  Father.  We  love  God  truly  as  a 
Father  when  we  love  Him  in  the  Son,  His  perfect  revelation. 
Since  love  to  God  in  Christ  surpasses  all  other  love,  even 
that  belonging  to  marriage  and  family  relationships,  Matt. 
xvi.  24,  X.  37,  it  is  the  principle  that  ought  to  regulate  all 
love.  All  individual  forms  of  good  are  subordinate  to  the 
good  of  being  a  child  of  God ;  if  any  other  good  takes  the 
highest  place  in  the  heart,  then  idolatry  arises.  It  is  this 
which  secures  our  freedom  in  all  circumstances  and  fortunes. 
The  good  of  fellowship  with  God,  which  the  world  cannot 
take  away,  is  able  to  elicit  spiritual  joy  even  from  suffermg, 
and  to  sanctify  our  joy,  Jas.  v.  13.  But  love  to  God 
assumes  the  chief  place  in  the  heart  in  such  wise  as  to  be 
the  germ  and  motive  power  of  all  other  love  which  is  of  a 
truly  moral  kind,  and  keeps  its  due  place.  All  sin  has  been 
defined  by  Augustine  as  "  amor  inordinatus."  N"o  individual 
thing  can  be  truly  loved  as  a  good,  unless  in  it  we  love  the 
Good  as  a  whole,  which  exists  originally  and  personally  in  God. 
2.  The  subjective  side  of  Christian  piety  or  love  to  God. 
This  is,  first  of  all,  according  to  Christ's  example,  grateful  love 
for  spiritual  and  physical  gifts,  Matt.  xi.  2  5  ;  John  vi.  11, 
xi.  41 ;  Eph.  v.  20  ;  also  for  gracious  acts  of  God,  above  all, 
redemption  and  forgiveness  of  sin,  and  for  blessings  conferred 
upon  others,  1  Thess.  v.  18 ;  2  Cor.  i.  11,  iv.  15.  But 
especially  is  it  thankful  for  love  itself;  and  here  gratitude 
rises  to  the  very  fountainhead  of  the  Good,  and  becomes 
praise  of  God.  Every  virtue  which  is  evinced  may  be  derived 
from  pious  gratitude,  as  is  done  by  the  Heidelberg  Catechism, 
but  contentment  and  patience  more  especially  are  inseparable 
'  rf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  iv.  §  127,  7. 


REVERENCE  AND  LOVE.  415 

from  it.  A  pretentious  and  discontented  man  is  always  un- 
thankful. On  the  other  hand,  Christian  gratitude  is  also  the 
mother  of  trust.  Ho  who  has  bestowed  upon  us  the  best  of 
all  things  in  Christ,  will  not  withhold  any  smaller  gift,  Heb. 
ii.  13,  iii.  6,  x.  35  ;  Eph.  iii.  12  ;  1  John  iv.  17  ;  Eom.  viii. 
15,  32;  Gal.  iv.  6;  PhH.  i.  6. 

3.  Reverence  and  Love.  The  Christian's  love  to  God,  being 
filial  love,  is  a  union  of  opposites — of  reverence  and  childlike 
trust,  Eeverence  seems  to  keep  its  object  at  a  distance, 
while  love  encourages  familiarity.  In  Christian  love  to  God, 
however,  there  is  none  of  the  fear  of  the  Old  Testament, 
Eom.  viii.  15;  1  John  iv.  18;  while,  nevertheless,  it  is  not 
irreverent,  not  a  love,  so  to  speak,  such  as  one  has  to  a 
companion.  There  is  aitm  in  it,  Heb.  xii.  28,  that  which  is 
also  called  "  (f)6^o<i "  in  the  New  Testament  sense  of  the  word. 
It  dreads  extending  its  fellowship  with  God  to  undue  famili- 
arity. It  is  not  love  on  equal  terms.  It  rests  on  gratitude ; 
the  Author  of  mental  and  spiritual  life  ever  remains  an 
absolute  authority  to  His  child ;  this  is  a  part  of  the  child's 
piety.  But  the  Christian,  too,  like  a  child  that  looks  up  to 
his  father,  looks  up  to  heaven,  into  which  he  has  an  entrance, 
Heb.  X.  19  f,  nay,  of  which  he  is  a  citizen,  Eph.  ii.  19.  Thus 
the  majesty  of  God  does  not  alienate  but  attract  him,  and  is 
the  sure  ground  upon  which  his  childlike  confidence  relies. 

4.  The  filial  relationship  exists  even  before  perfection,  even 
along  with  much  weakness,  error,  and  sin ;  nay,  without  it 
perfection  could  never  be  attained ;  it  is  the  highest  personal 
good,  because  it  is  fellowship  of  the  individual  person  with 
the  Triune  God,  not  merely  so-called  moral  fellowship,  but 
participation  in  God's  life  and  spirit,  2  Pet.  i.  4.  The 
believer  is  a  brother  of  Christ,  the  first  -  born,  Eom. 
viii.  29;  1  Cor.  xv.  20,  49;  Col.  i.  18;  Heb.  ii.  11,  17. 
He  knows  that  he  is  thought,  known,  and  loved  by  God, 
that  he  has  been  translated  into  the  sphere  of  light, 
and  given  the  hope  of  a  crown  that  fadeth  not  away,  Col. 
i.  12  ;  1  Pet.  v.  4.  The  separate  moments  in  this  good  of 
sonsJiip  are — (1)  on  the  negative  side,  emancipation  from  a 
state  of  disunion  with  oneself  and  with  God,  Eom.  v.  1,  from 
the  consciousness  of  guilt  and  j^unishment,  Eom.  viii.  1,  and 
in  addition,  freedom  from  legalism  and    fear,  Eom.  viii.  15, 


416       §  51.    CHRISTIAN  PIETY  AS  CONTEMPLATION  AND  PEAYER. 

Gal,  iv.  6,  and  from  hondac/c  to  human  authority,  Gal.  v.  1  ; 

1  Cor.  vii.  23.  (2)  Its  positive  moments  are — the  feeling  of 
peace  through  experience  of  the  love  of  God,  Eom.  v.  5,  true 
knowledge  of  God,  the  unfathomable  depths  of  God,  and  above 
all  of  His  love,  being  opened  up  through  the  Son  of  His 
love,  and  the  neiu  irrinciijle  of  love  to  God.  All  this  is 
(Eom.  viii.  21)  comprehended  in  the  "glorious  liberty  of  the 
children  of  God"  which  the  iiaTaiOT7]<i  of  the  world  and  its 
ills  cannot  affect,  for  ills  themselves  now  become  •uaihda, 
and  consequently  benefits,  Heb.  xii.  5.  ISTay,  mention  is  even 
made  of  a  (rvii^acrCKeveiv  of  believers  with  Christ,  Eom.  v.  1 7  ; 

2  Tim.  ii.  12.      But  love  to  God  has  also  an  active  side. 

§  51. 

B. — Christian  Piety  as  Inward  Activity,  or  Contemplation 
and  Prayer. 

The  (inward)  activity  of  piety  as  such  consists  in — (1)  a 
turning  of  the  soul  from  without  inwards,  i.e.  spiritual 
contemplation,  or  knowledge  in  the  character  of  edifica- 
tion ;  (2)  a  movement  from  within  outwards  toward 
God,  i.e.  prayer,  which  consists  partly  of  petition  and 
intercession,  partly  of  thanksgiving,  adoration,  and  praise, 
and  attains  perfection  both  of  form  and  contents  by  being 
offered  in  the  name  of  Jesus.  [Cf.  System  of  Christian 
Doctrine,  ii.  §  48  ;  cf.  p.  446  :  ii.  2,  §  127,  6,  7,  146&.] 

The  LiTEiiATUKE.  —  Stiiudlin,  Geschichte  der  Lehre  von  den 
Vorstellungcn  vom  Gebet,  1824.  Fenelon,  Discours  sur  Ice  prih-c. 
Lober,  Das  Lelcn  in  Gott.  Die  Lehre  vom  Gebet,  1860.  Gess, 
Vortrag  ilber  das  Gebet.  Eieger,  Herzenspostille,  VJ4l2,  pp.  40  f., 
412  £,  765  f.  [Schleiermacher,  Der  Christliehe  Glaube,  ii.  p. 
430  f.  Monrad,  Aus  der  Welt  des  Gebets,  2nd  ed.  1878. 
Culmann,  Christl.  Ethik,  i.  p.  157  f.  Eitschl,  Rechtfertigung 
unci  Versohnung,  iii.  c.  9.  Martensen,  I.e.  ii.  1,  p.  207  f. 
Eothe,  2nd  ed.  ii.  pp.  173-194.  Hofmann,  Theol.  Ethik,  pp. 
129-155.] 

1.  The  Christian  has  access  to  the  fountain  of  a  higher 
spiritual  vitality  than  that  which  is  open  to  other  men,  a 
vitality  which  is  not  of  an  external  kind,  either  physical  or 


CONTEMPLATION.  417 

psycliical,  but  is  inward  and  spiritual,  Eom.  xii.  1 1  ;  2  Tim. 
i.  6,  ava^coTTvpelv ;  Col.  i.  11.  From  this  fountain  there  flow 
to  him  quickening  influences,  that  aflect  the  soul,  nay,  even 
the  body.  The  irvevixa  imparts  living  efficiency  to  the  higher 
impulses,  strengthens  intelligence  and  will,  and  quickens 
feeling,  and  all  these  effects  in  union  constitute  "  inspiration." 
Inspiration  in  its  highest  and  purest  form  is  no  ecstatic 
excitement,  but  a  steady,  pure  flame,  coupled  with  clearness  of 
spiritual  vision,  while  life  preserves  its  steadiness  and  balance. 
Thus  it  is  that  spiritual  warmth  of  life  which  is  opposed  alike 
to  coldness  and  lukewarmness,  Eev.  iii.  15,  16  (■x\(,ap6<;, 
^jrvxpo'i,  ^ec7T09).  The  Christian  has  a  ferment  in  his  spirit, 
(^eeiv  TTvevfiari,,  Eom.  xii.  11,  a  good  f^Xo?,  that  in  his  inward 
life  shows  itself  specially  in  the  desire  to  be  occupied  with 
(rod  and  divine  things.  This  desire  is  carried  into  effect  in 
the  two  forms  of  contemplation  and  prayer,  which  mutually 
quicken  each  other,  and  are  characteristic  of  the  pious  life, 
both  individual  and  social. 

2.  Necessity  of  contemplation  and  prayer.  These  are  neces- 
sary, not  only  as  a  manifestation  of  piety,  but  also  as  a  means 
of  strength,  as  a  religious  means  of  virtue  (§  48,  4).  The  sin 
which  cleaves  to  us  is  always  making  us  languid  and  indolent, 
Heb.  xii.  12.  In  this  state  of  matters  our  work  is  apt  to  be 
carried  on  from  a  mere  force  of  habit  due  to  some  former 
higher  impulse  that  we  have  formerly  received,  whilst  conflict 
and  victory  call  for  the  constant  renewal  of  such  impulses. 
Hence  we  must  collect  ourselves  again,  and  not  let  ourselves 
live  upon  our  own  strength,  for,  in  other  words,  this  would 
be  to  fall  into  Pelagianism.  The  fundamental  relation  of  the 
Christian  never  changes ;  he  seeks,  by  means  of  contemplation 
and  prayer,  to  derive  power  for  good  from  the  one  original 
Good,  viz.  the  personal  God  in  Christ;  and  for  this  end, 
whatever  good  he  already  possesses  is  brought  into  requisition. 
We  will  consider  more  closely — 

I.  Contemplation. 

§  52.   Continuation. 

I.  Contemplation. 

1.  The  necessity  of  contemplation  is  borne  witness  to  in 
various  ways  by  Scripture  and  its  injunctions,  see  John  v.  39  ; 

2  D 


418  §  52.    CONTINUATION. 

1  Cor.  X.  11  ;  Acts  xvii.  11 ;  2  Tim.  iii.  14  f. ;  2  Pet.  i.  19  , 
in  which  passages  sacred  Scripture  is  frequently  pointed 
out  as  a  means  of  edification,  on  the  ground  of  its  being  the 
record  of  the  chain  of  saving  acts  which  God  wrought  on 
humanity,  and  of  its  presenting  us  with  the  classic  form  of 
piety.  And  here  the  Old  Testament  is  included  along  with 
the  New,  but  with  this  qualification,  that  it  is  Christianity 
which  first  gives  to  it  its  true  interpretation,  2  Cor.  iii. ;  1  Cor. 
X.  1  f.  In  contemplation,  the  spirit,  collecting  itself  from 
amid  the  distracting  "  many  things  "  of  life,  and  falling  back 
upon  the  "  one  thing,"  Luke  x,  42,  breaks  loose  from  that  flood 
of  daily  thoughts,  cares,  and  occupations  in  which  its  vision  so 
soon  becomes  limited  and  dim,  brings  all  things  into  the  light 
of  the  divine,  and  views  them  in  a  religious  aspect,  sub  sjjecie 
ceternitatis.  This  has  a  purifying  effect,  and  aids  self-examina- 
tion and  self-knowledge.  Through  contemplation  we  are 
consciously  raised  from  time  to  time  above  external  things, 
instead  of  becoming  their  slaves,  and  regard  them  in  some 
measure  as  God  does.  But  from  the  one  thing  we  again 
return  to  the  many,  and  see  in  the  world  the  revelation  of 
God  and  the  sphere  of  His  activity,  and  thus  consecrate  our 
daily  work  and  the  field  where  it  is  plied,  be  it  small  or  great. 
Let  us  now  dwell  upon  the  nature,  the  object,  and  the  mode  of 
contemplation. 

2.  The  essential  nature  of  contemplation  is  cognition  under 
the  character  of  edification,  otKoSo/jbt],  as  is  shown  by  the  fact 
that  when  contemplation  fulfils  its  aim,  it  naturally  passes 
over  into  prayer.  For  although  contemplation  is  religious 
cognitio7i,  it  is  not  wholly  or  even  chiefly  taken  up  with  the 
extension  of  knowledge,  as  if  it  could  be  completely  satisfied 
with  making  new  acquisitions.  But  Christian  contemplation, 
having  edification  as  its  aim,  seeks,  above  all  things,  to  give 
life  to  the  knowledge  that  is  already  possessed,  and  to  main- 
tain the  living  stedfastness  of  the  spirit  in  the  truth.  At  the 
same  time,  of  course,  new  views  of  truth  are  continually 
opening  up  of  themselves.  Thus  to  make  truth  that  is  old, 
yet  ever  new,  a  living  power  in  the  hearts  of  men  is  the  main 
art  in  preacliing,  and  a  difficult  one.  It  is  easy  enough  to  say 
something  new,  especially  in  such  an  intellectual  age  as  our 
own ;  it  is  still  easier  to  launch  out  into  constant  repetition 


THE  OBJECT  OF  CONTEMPLATION.  419 

of  traditional  dogmas  and  formulas.  But  it  is  a  more  difficult 
matter  for  the  preacher  actually  so  to  place  his  hearers  in  the 
kingdom  of  truth,  that  they  observe  for  themselves,  that  they 
breathe,  feel,  and  think  in  it  as  in  a  really  existing  world,  and 
feel  that  they  are  built  up  on  a  divine  foundation.  But 
wherever  this  is  done  a  divine  work  has  been  accomplished,  a 
part  of  the  progressive  history  of  redemption,  of  the  history  of 
the  divine  life  in  the  world,  has  taken  place,  Eph.  ii.  20  fi'., 
iv.  12,  29  ;  1  Cor.  xiv.  26,  x.  23.  Without  such  substantial 
oIko8o/j,7]  every  new  thing  soon  becomes  old,  and  loses  its 
charm  and  its  savour.  Christian  contemplation  accomplishes 
the  ends  we  have  mentioned  when  it  is  not  merely  objective 
thinking  or  a  statement  of  the  Jidcs  historica,  whether  of  a 
learned,  scientific,  dialectic,  or  speculative  kind,  but  when  it  is 
aflame  with  living  faith  and  love  to  God,  and  consequently 
the  whole  soul  is  engaged  in  it. 

3.  The  object  of  contemplation  is  God  and  His  deeds  in 
creation  and  the  government  of  the  universe.  Its  most 
important  field  is  history,  especially  the  sacred  history  that  is 
stored  up  in  the  Bible.  Since  the  deeds  recorded  in  sacred 
history  reveal  what  is  eternal,  sacred  history  is  both  fruitful 
and  applicable  with  regard  to  the  present  and  the  future.  It 
is  well  known  that  simple  people  who  read  nothing  but 
the  Bible,  nevertheless  gain  from  it  a  treasure  of  Christian 
wisdom  for  the  conduct  of  life.  The  Old  Testament  supplies 
us  with  a  rich  history  of  families  and  peoples,  as  well  as  of 
individual  lives ;  a  connected  account,  typical  for  all  time,  of 
the  divine  education  of  humanity,  a  key  that  also  enables 
us  to  understand  the  history  of  Christian  nations.  For  the 
latter,  too,  may  and  ought  to  become  more  and  more  an  object 
for  Christian  contemplation,  since  it  would  be  unbelief  to 
suppose  that  in  the  Christian  age  God's  guidance  and  govern- 
ment are  less  real  and  have  less  purpose  in  them  than  in 
ancient  times.  Were  this  done  more  than  it  is,  and  had  we 
such  a  clear,  religious  comprehension  of  the  way  in  which 
each  nation  has  been  led,  as  the  historical  books  of  the 
Old  Testament  afford  with  regard  to  the  history  of  Israel, 
we  should  have  something  substantial  wherewith  to  counter- 
balance the  theories  of  the  moment,  something  to  oppose  to 
the  distraction  and  confusion  of  judgment  caused  by  th3  aber- 


420  §  52.    CONTINUATION. 

niLioiis  of  the  present  time,  and  the  discordant  voices  that  are 
heard  in  literature,  in  journals,  etc.  It  is  much  to  be  desired 
that  we  had  also  a  literature  clearly  and  truthfully  exhibiting 
the  deliverances  God  has  wrought  and  the  deeds  He  has  done 
for  "humanity  and  for  our  own  nation,  and  deeply  impressing 
upon  our  people  their  conversion  to  Christianity.  A  begin- 
ning has  been  made  on  the  side  of  the  Church  for  diffusing 
among  the  people  information  of  this  kind  concerning  the 
lieroes  of  the  Church  and  the  great  deeds  of  God  in  the 
Church's  history.  This  is  the  idea  of  the  Evangelical  Christian 
Calendar,  an  idea  already  entertained  by  Melanchthon.  And 
from  the  calendar  annals  might  arise. 

But  not  only  history,  nature  too  is  an  object  of  religious 
contemplation  for  the  Christian.  It  is  true  that  nature  is 
perishable,  Eom.  viii.  20  ;  but  still  it  is  a  sphere  where  God 
reveals  Himself,  Ps.  xix.,  xxix.,  xxxiii.,  civ.,  cxlviii.,  Eom.  i.  20, 
and  intercourse  with  it  refreshes  botli  soul  and  senses,  and  is 
therefore  of  great  importance  for  the  work  of  virtue  in  which 
the  Christian  is  engaged.  Our  Saviour,  too,  was  far  from  exhibit- 
ing any  super-spirituality  or  alienation  towards  nature.  His 
eye  dwelt  with  love  upon  the  lilies  of  the  field  and  the  birds 
of  heaven.  His  parables  especially  evince  His  holy  love  of 
nature,  and  show  at  the  same  time  how  He  recognises  the 
inner  harmony  that  subsists  between  the  first  creation  and 
the  second.  To  Him  nature  furnishes  types  or  similitudes 
of  those  laws  of  life  which  appear  in  their  higher  potency 
in  His  kingdom.  He  preaches  that  God  provides  for  animated 
nature  also,  and  from  it  He  derives  the  fairest  images  in  that 
realistic  language  of  His  which  is  so  full  of  plastic  force, 
John  X.  1  ff.,  XV.  1  ff.  To  Him  God  is  present  and  visible  in 
nature  also.  But  none  the  less,  God  is  to  Him,  not  merely 
the  God  of  nature,  but  a  Father.  Our  religious  contempla- 
tion of  nature  and  history  must  not,  however,  so  lose  sight 
of  the  real  world,  as  merely  to  rise  to  universal  views  of 
the  divine  attributes ;  the  important  thing  is  to  lay  hold,  as 
it  were,  of  God  in  His  living  activity  in  nature  and  history. 
When  this  is  done,  contemplation  is  altogether  detached  from 
mere  curiosity  or  the  mere  accumulation  of  knowledge — that 
is,  from  the  deification  of  nature  or  of  man.  The  tliircl  main 
object  of  contemplation  is  oneself,  and  all  contemplation  must. 


SELF-INSPECTIOX.  421 

in  the  last  resort,  liave  reference  to  sclf-lcnowkdfje,  1  Cor.  xi.  28. 
Even  the  old  heathen  saues  recognised  the  importance  of 
self-knowledge.  Here  self-inspection,  which  is  a  means  of 
purification  and  growth  for  the  Christian,  must  be  taken  into 
consideration ;  and  as  this  is  an  important  subject,  we  will 
add  a  few  remarks  as  to  the  right  manner  of  conducting 
self-inspection,  and  so  acquiring  self-knowledge. 

4.  The  kind  and  manner  of  CJiristian  contemplation  in 
self-inspection.  On  the  subjective  side,  stillness  and  collected- 
ness  are  requisite,  in  order  that  the  objective  means — the 
word  and  sacraments  of  God,  and  the  contemplation  of  nature 
and  history  —  may  take  eifect.  Christ  by  His  example 
])ermits  and  recommends  us  not  to  be  always  in  society, 
but  to  seek  solitude  from  time  to  time,  either  in  the  stillness 
of  nature  or  in  the  closet.  Matt.  vi.  6  ;  John  vi.  15;  Luke 
vi.  12.  It  is  no  good  sign  for  a  man's  conscience  or  for  his 
spirituality,  when  he  shuns  solitude,  whether  it  be  that 
he  is  afraid  of  his  own  thoughts,  or  because  he  finds  self- 
contemplation  to  be  a  weariness  and  a  duty  which  he  has  not 
strength  to  discharge.  Self-examination  and  self-inspection 
may  be  steadily  maintained  by  the  use  of  diaries,  which 
are  a  means  of  resisting  frivolity  and  distraction,  and  are 
fitted  to  accustom  us  to  turn  our  attention  upon  ourselves, 
and  to  give  account  of  our  day's  work  or  of  the  different 
portions  of  our  time.  Still  there  are  also  dangers  to  be 
avoided  here.  Slackness  of  conscience  and  self-love  are  ever 
ready  to  make  self- inspection  an  occasion  of  self- display, 
of  comparing  ourselves  with  others,  Luke  xviii.  11  ff.,  of  self- 
complacency,  and  of  taking  a  poisonous  pleasure  in  self. 
Such  Narcissus-like  thoughts  unhinge  us,  and  must  be  expelled 
by  the  stern  earnestness  of  God's  holy  law.  Again,  when  the 
conscience  is  more  active,  Ave  must  avoid  the  danger  of  Ijrooding 
over  our  sins,  a  habit  which,  taking  the  form  of  self-accusation, 
may  either  cause  us  to  feel  pleased  with  ourselves  (in  secret, 
at  least)  on  account  of  our  very  self-censure,  or  may  quite 
dishearten  us.  Instead  of  this,  the  Christian  looks  at  himself 
as  a  whole,  and  in  the  consciousness  of  his  own  impotence, 
fixes  his  gaze  in  childlike  confidence  on  Christ,  who  alone 
has  positive  power  to  heal.  For  even  though  he  knew  all 
his  sins  one  by  one,  the  knowledge  would  not  cure  him.     The 


422  §  53.    CONTINUATION. 

important  matter  is,  that  his  knowledge  of  himself  as  a  whole 
should  impress  him  powerfully,  not  that  he  should  lose  him- 
self amid  the  casual  details  of  his  life.  Speaking  generally, 
self-inspection  must  not  degenerate  into  a  magnifying  of  our 
own  small  importance.  Nor  does  it  afford  any  real  help  to 
the  Christian  merely  to  gaze  unweariedly  at  his  sins  and 
infirmities,  instead  of  comprehending  all  this  multiplicity  in 
one  piercing,  humbling  glance,  and  going  with  it  to  the  true 
Physician.  Forward  to  the  goal,  upward  to  Christ — this  must 
be  the  cry  of  him  who  is  in  earnest  about  his  soul.  Self-inspec- 
tion which  does  not  draw  us  to  this  centre,  however  severe 
and  earnest  it  may  seem  to  be,  nevertheless  misses  the  funda- 
mental error  of  all,  and  is  but  a  distraction. 

With  men  of  a  more  earnest  stamp  the  habit  of  brooding 
has  special  reference  to  indications  of  regeneration,  and  these 
are  only  too  apt  to  be  laid  down  in  an  arbitrary  way.  But 
we  must  not  forget  that  it  is  not  signs  that  make  us  good, 
but  that  a  good  tree  bringeth  forth  good  fruits.  If  a  man  is 
troubled  lest  he  be  not  among  the  elect  or  the  converted,  let 
him  only  see  to  it  that  he  has  faith,  that  he  looks  to  Christ, 
that  he  keeps  the  doors  of  his  soul  wide  open  to  receive  the 
gifts  of  Christ,  among  which  in  due  season  will  be  numbered 
an  established  heart.  For  our  future  we  need  and  can  find 
no  other  guarantee  than  the  faithful  and  gracious  purpose  of 
Christ,  Phil.  i.  6,  who  will  perfect  the  work  that  has  been 
begun.  The  chief  means  of  fellowship  with  Christ,  however, 
is  communion  with  Him  in  prayer. 

§  53.   Contimtation. 

II.    PllAYER. 

For  the  Literature,  cf.  §  51. 

1.  The  simplest  definition  of  prayer  is  that  it  is  the  talk 
or  conversation  of  the  soul  with  God  as  a  present  Being ;  not 
a  monologue,  as  was  the  prayer  of  the  Pharisee  in  the  temple, 
Luke  xviii.  11.^  In  numberless  passages  the  New  Testament 
exhorts  us  to  prayer,  Matt.  vi.  5,  xxvi.  41  ;  Luke  xviii.  1, 
xxii.  43  ;  John  xvi.  23  ;   1  John  iii.   19-22  ;  Eom.  viii.  26. 


PRAYER.  423 

Christ  Himself  prayed  in  the  form  of  petition,  thanksgiving, 
and  praise,  Matt.  xi.  25,  xiv.  23  ;  Luke  vi.  12  ;  Matt.  xxvi. 
36,  39,  42,44;  John  xvii.,  xi.  41.  Prayer  is  the  specific 
means  of  growth  in  the  inner  life.  Other  things  may  stimu- 
late us  to  use  the  power  we  already  have,  but  prayer  increases 
our  stock  of  spiritual  life  by  drawing  down  upon  us  in  richer 
measure  the  fulness  of  the  Holy  Spirit,  and  thus  making  our 
human  life  divine.  Through  prayer  Christ  Himself  was  made 
perfect ;  and  so  are  all  the  children  of  God.  Thus  it  is  a 
means  of  virtue  in  quite  a  special  sense,  and  not  merely  a 
manifestation  of  the  life  already  possessed.  But  prayer  is 
intended  to  lead  the  Christian  life  to  a  purer  form  of  mani- 
festation, to  childlike  converse  with  God  ;  and  this  is  in  itself 
a  valuable  good.  The  wings  of  the  soul  are  strengthened 
through  prayer ;  fervour,  zeal,  and  enthusiasm  are  kindled,  and 
by  this  means  our  natural  gifts  are  inspired  and  become 
charismata.  But  further,  in  learning  to  pray  aright,  watch- 
fulness is  a  great  assistance.  "  Watch  and  pray  " — self- 
recollection ;  Matt.  xxvi.  41,  xxiv.  42;  1  Pet.  v.  8;  Eev. 
iii.  2  ;  1  Cor,  xvi.  13.  Watchfulness  and  sobriety  of  mind 
remind  us  at  once  of  our  own  weakness  and  of  the  power  and 
love  of  God.  Seeking  God  presupposes  self-distrust,  and  peace 
presupposes  seeking  God ;  and  we  must  seek  God  before  we 
can  have  peace.  We  can,  moreover,  only  learn  to  pray  by 
praying,  however  awkward  our  attempts  may  be.  The 
principal  rule  for  successful  prayer  is  first  of  all  to  will  to 
pray  rightly,  and  therefore  we  must  first  of  all  ask  for  the  spirit 
of  prayer,  to  be  enabled  to  pray  aright.  By  this  means  we 
combat  dissipation,  dulness,  dryness,  and  the  spirit  which 
shuts  itself  up  within  itself.  The  suppliant  confesses  that 
he  is  involved  in  all  these  failings,  but  against  his  will ;  and 
so  he  gets  the  blessing  of  collectedness,  lively  aspiration, 
clearness  and  openness  to  the  Spirit  of  God.  Thereupon  he 
can  proceed  to  drink  refreshing  draughts  from  the  divine 
fountain  ;  and  then  follows  his  response  to  the  divine  gifts — 
joy  in  God,  love  and  thankfulness  toward  Him.  Christian 
prayer  has  two  chief  forms,  according  as  it  is  meant  to  express 
a  need  or  joy  at  the  satisfaction  of  a  need.  It  is  petition  or 
thanksgi-ving . 

2.  Petition    with  intercession.     With    Christ,  petition  and 


424  §  53.    CONTINUATIOX. 

thanksgiving  were  never  separated.  In  the  very  act  of 
asking  for  anything,  it  was  His  custom  to  give  thanks.  He 
gives  thanks  because  it  comes  ;  and  it  comes  because  He  prays 
who  makes  all  prayer  acceptable.  What  He  prayed  for  came 
to  pass ;  He  is  the  free  Son  of  man,,  who,  whilst  praying,  takes 
part  in  the  government  of  the  world.  The  Son  stood  con- 
sciously within  the  Father's  will,  nothing  happened  to  Him 
that  He  had  not  ordained  ;  so  utterly  removed  was  He  from 
all  passivity  ;  so  completely  in  His  case  was  fate  trans- 
figured into  freedom.  Now  we  cannot  pray  directly  in  this 
fashion  ;  but  we  are  encouraged  by  Christ  to  pray  in  His 
name.  In  so  doing,  we  put  ourselves  by  faith  into  Christ, 
into  His  place ;  in  such  wise  that  we  beseech  Him  to 
embrace  us  in  His  substitutionary  love,  or  to  pray  for  us, 
and  thus  be  what  Scripture  calls  our  mediator  or  intercessor 
with  the  Father,  Eom.  viii.  26,  34.  When  this  rci'p'port  has 
been  established  between  the  Head  and  the  members,  the 
promise  attached  to  the  prayers  of  Christ  holds  good  also  for 
those  of  His  members.  Their  prayers,  offered  in  His  name, 
are  a  continuation  of  His  life.  Very  numerous  passages  of 
Scripture  describe  the  value  of  prayer  in  the  name  of  Jesus, 
and  its  acceptation  with  God,  Matt.  xxi.  22  ;  Luke  xi.  13, 
xviii.  7  ;  John  xv.  7,  16,xvi.  23  ;  Eom.  xv.  30  ;  2  Cor.  i.  11  ; 
Phil.  i.  19  ;  1  Pet.  iii.  12  ;  Jas.  i.  5,  iv.  2,  3,  v.  14.  Prayer 
in  Christ's  name  is  therefore  prayer  proceeding  from  our 
fellowship  with  Christ  and  Christ's  fellowship  with  us,  so 
that  we  enter  into  His  mind  and  spirit,  and  speak  as 
commissioned,  authorized,  and  enabled  by  Him,  Wherever 
this  takes  place,  wherever  the  mind  of  Christ  is,  there  too 
that  which  is  right  will  come  into  our  mind  ;  at  all  events, 
everything  will  be  discarded  at  the  outset,  which,  according 
to  God's  decree,  ought  not  to  be  prayed  for ;  everything, 
whether  of  a  material  or  even  of  a  spiritual  kind,  if  it  lie 
outside  the  dispositions  of  divine  wisdom.  Such  prayer,  being 
believing  prayer,  is  then  powerful  and  acceptable  with  God. 
Here  we  must  assume  —  as  is  shown  in  Dogmatics  ^ —  that 
the  efficacy  of  prayer,  being  interwoven  with  the  divine  world- 
plan,  is  entirely  consistent  with  the  divine  government  of 
the  world.  Christian  prayer  and  its  fulfilment  harmonize, 
1  Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  i.  §  32,  5,  ii.  §  48  ;  cf.  §  37. 


PETITION  WITH  INTERCESSION".  425 

because  they  have  07ic  and  the  same  supreme  source.  Peti- 
tionary prayer  in  the  name  of  Jesus  is  a  presentiment  wrought 
in  us  by  the  Holy  Spirit,  and  its  fulfilment  is  the  correspond- 
ing activity  of  God,  which  He  puts  forth  because  the  prayer 
of  the  believer  proves  that  the  world  is  ready  to  receive  it. 

From  the  exposition  that  has  been  given,  we  see  that 
petitionary  prayer,  offered  in  the  name  of  Jesus,  excludes  ttvo 
extremes.  There  are  some  who  indeed  regard  faith  as  necessary 
to  prayer,  but  only  in  the  general  sense  of  trusting  that  God 
will  do  all  things  ivell.  They  therefore  deny  that  prayer 
should  refer  to  anything  definite  and  iiarticidar.  According 
to  them,  sid)mission  alone  is  Christian ;  to  apply  the  divine 
promise  to  any  particular  thing  is  presumption.  Such  is 
the  verdict  of  Ammon  upon  that  prayer  of  Luther  offered 
during  the  sickness  of  Melanchthon,  although  it  was  heard. 
But  if  Christians  ought  not  to  ask  in  confident  faith  for 
anything  definite,  they  would  still  be  in  their  minority,  not 
knowing  what  their  Lord  doeth.  They  could  never  under- 
take any  work  in  joyful  faith,  in  the  assured  confidence  that 
it  would  succeed.  On  the  contrary,  their  participation  in 
any  matter  would  be  only  hypothetical,  for  we  must  never 
engage  in  anything  to  a  greater  extent  than  we  can  give 
expression  to  in  prayer.  And  then  the  question  as  to 
wliether  prayer  is  heard  would  be  settled  by  saying  that  the 
believer  ought  not  to  pray  that  anything  definite  should  be 
granted.  But  this  would  mak^  the  life  of  the  Christian  poor 
and  colourless,  and  deprive  him  of  that  wisdom  whicli 
anticipates  what  the  kingdom  of  God  requires  at  the  present 
moment.  The  New  Testament  speaks  quite  differently.  It 
tells  us  we  should  be  related  to  God  as  children  to  a  father, 
Ptom.  viii.  15  ;  Gal.  iv.  6.  No  barriers  prevent  us  from 
bringing  all  our  concerns  before  God.  One  thing  only  is 
demanded — that  our  prayer  be  offered  in  the  name  of  Christ, 
i.e.  that  our  wishes  be  purified  by  our  fellowship  with  Christ. 
And  this  does  not  mean  that  we  are  to  desire  nothing,  to  be 
simply  resigned  ;  on  the  contrary,  it  means  that  out  of  its 
submission  to  God's  will,  faith  should  rise  again,  well  advised 
as  to  what  the  will  of  God  really  is,  enlightened  and  ready  to 
act  with  confidence.  Simple  submission  is  often  necessary, 
since  humility  always  remains  the  fundamental  characteristic 


42 G  §  53.    CONTINUATION-. 

of  the  Christian  as  a  child  of  God.  But  submission  is  never- 
theless short  of  perfection.  Even  the  prayer  of  Jesus  in 
Gethsemane  was  more  than  mere  submission;  it  became 
assured  conviction  of  what  the  will  of  God  was,  allied 
with  the  will  and  the  power  to  fullil  it.  The  other  extreme 
is  Theurrjic  Prayer,  which  simply  adheres  to  the  fact  that 
Christ  has  said,  "  Whatsoever  ye  shall  ask  in  my  name,  ye 
shall  receive."  Here  God  is  conceived  of  as  compelled 
by  prayer,  or  a  kind  of  magical  power  is  attributed  to 
certain  formulas.  This  would  be  to  make  God  entirely  passive 
in  relation  to  man,  just  as  in  the  other  case  man  was  made 
entirely  passive  in  relation  to  God.  But  this  is  irreverent  and 
unchildlike.  The  cure  for  this  extreme  lies  once  more  in 
prayer  in  the  name  of  Jesus.  When  we  pray  in  His  name, 
we  lay  every  wish  before  Christ,  and  before  giving  it  a  fixed 
shape,  seek  to  realize  that  fellowship  with  Christ  which, 
wherever  it  exists,  not  only  sweeps  away  all  carnally  egoistic 
and  foolish  wishes,  but  also  makes  the  prayer  that  now 
ascends  an  agency  of  the  Spirit  of  God,  and  consequently  a 
prayer  that  is  heard. 

Although  the  question  whether  prayer,  which  is  a  free  act, 
introduces  any  change  into  God's  government  of  the  world, 
belongs  to  Dogmatics,  still  it  is  clear  on  etliical  principles  also 
that  we  must  hold  an  active  reciprocal  relation  to  subsist 
between  God  and  His  children.  Accordingly,  the  so-called 
passive  prayer  of  Molinos  is  also  objectionable.  According  to 
him,  God  alone  is  said  to  pray  in  man.  To  this  we  reply :  it 
is  true  that  no  prayer  is  successful  in  which  we  have  not  the 
co-operation  of  the  Spirit  of  God  in  our  hearts ;  but  this  does 
not  mean  that  He  becomes  our  substitute,  to  the  exclusion  of 
our  own  activity,  but  that  His  operation  is  positive,  and 
a  definite  act.  And  the  act  of  the  Holy  Spirit  is  the  cause  of 
prayer  in  this  sense,  that  the  prayer  of  the  Christian  is  at 
once  human  and  divine,  and  its  imperfection  is  compensated 
for  by  fellowship  with  the  Triune  God. 

Petitionary  inayer,  if  only  it  be  offered  in  the  name  of 
Jesus,  may  have  reference  also  to  hoclily  2vants,—a,s  we  see 
from  the  Lord's  Prayer, — although  these  must  come  in  their 
proper  place.  Spiritualism  insists  that  the  "bread"  here 
spoken  of  is  spiritual  bread.      He,  however,  who  is  unwilling 


THANKSGIVING  AND  PRAISE.  427 

to  pray  for  what  is  necessary  for  the  body,  will  not  give 
thanks  for  it.  A  test  of  the  purity  of  all  our  petitionary 
prayers  is  whether  they  contain  intercession.  This  shows  if 
the  individual  he  concerned  about  the  whole  kingdom  of  God. 
Without  intercession  prayer  becomes  egoistic,  the  view  and 
the  heart  narrow.  When  piety  lacks  expansion,  it  also  lacks 
intensive  force.  And  then  our  prayer  is  not  prayer  in  the 
name  of  Jesus  our  Head. 

3.    Thanksgiving   and  imiisc.      Thanksgiving  also  must  be 
nmde   in  the   name   of    Jesus,   in   order   that  we  may   give 
thanks  for  the  right  thing  and  in  the  right  sense,  and  that 
we   may   not   misunderstand   God's   kindness   and  His  gifts, 
which  may  be  shown  even  in  the  infliction  of  suffering  and 
loss.     Here,  too,  both  the  universal  and  the  particular  must 
be    made    the    subject    of    thanksgiving.      The    test    of   the 
purity  of  this  form   of  prayer   is   whether   we   give   thanks 
for  the  good  that  happens  to  others  as  well  as  for  that  which 
happens  to  ourselves.    This  makes  thanksgiving  the  Christian's 
victory  over  envy,  jealousy,  and  pride.     Thanksgiving,  more- 
over, shows  the  measure  of  our  gratitude,  and  gratitude  of  our 
humility.      Where  there  is  ingratitude  there  is  much  pride. 
All  wilful,  restless  desires  sink  to  rest  when  we  give  thanks 
for  what  we  truly  ought.      Such  thanksgiving,  although  it  is 
some  individual  thing  that  gives  rise  to  it,  is  praise  of  God 
Himself,   and   is   pleasing   to   God.       In    thanksgiving,   man 
renders  back  to  God  as  a  spiritual  offering  the  divine  benefit 
he  has  received,  by  bringing  it  clearly  before  his  mind  in  the 
sacrifice  of  prayer  as  something  presented  to  him  by  God ; 
and  then  receives  the   gift  again  in  a  higher  form,  enriched 
with   the    consciousness   that   in   it   God's   love   is  bestowed 
upon  him.     The  more   our  thanksgiving  melts  into  joy  and 
delight  in  this  love  of  God  and  Christ,  the  purer  will  it  be. 
It  then  becomes  p-aisc  of  God.      Further,  just  as  no  peti- 
tionary prayer  is  Christian  which  proceeds  as  if  there   were 
as  yet  nothing  to  give  thanks  for,  so  Christian  thanksgiving 
must    also    include    petition    as    a    moment.     This,   too,    is 
pleasing   to    God.     The    kingdom  of  God  is  here,  but  it  is 
also  coming.     Premature  contentment  would  be  self-deception 
with  regard   to   oneself  or  the   world,  if  not  indifference  and 
lovelessness.       The   prayer  of   petition   that   springs   from   a 


428  §  53.    CONTINUATION. 

grateful  heart,  asks  for  new  strength  in  God,  in  the  knowledge 
of  His  majesty,  holiness,  and  blessedness,  and  then  passes 
over  to  the  thought  of  the  practical  life,  to  the  world  in 
its  alienation  from  God,  and  the  valiant  conflict  we  must 
wage  therein.  This  is  the  course  followed  by  the  Lord's 
Prayer. 

-i.  TJie  form  of  jjraycr.  Its  inner  form  has  already  been 
determined  in  requiring  that  it  be  offered  in  the  name  of 
Jesus.  But  the  question  still  remains  as  to  the  position  of 
oratio  vcrhalis  and  mentalis.  Is  it  not  sufficient  that  prayer 
should  exist  inwardly,  as  a  longing,  an  inward  emotion  or 
affection  ?  Can  it  serve  any  purpose  to  clothe  our  prayer  in 
words  and  give  it  outward  expression  before  God,  aloud  or  in 
a  whisper,  when  we  remember  that  God  looks  into  the  heart, 
and  knows  all  our  desires  as  well  as  all  our  wants  ?  Matt.  vi.  8. 
The  inward  emotion  must  indeed  be  the  first  thing,  though  it 
be  no  more  than  the  desire  to  be  enabled  to  pray.  But  when 
this  emotion  does  not  clothe  itself  in  definite  thoughts  and 
words,  prayer  is  still  imperfect,  not  in  intensity,  but  in 
definiteness — although  it  is  not  always  possible  in  the  stress 
of  circumstances  to  clothe  our  prayer  in  thoughts  and  words. 
Itom.  viri.  26.  At  such  times  a-revayixol  dXaX.rjroc  rise  from  the 
heart.  The  prayer  of  the  publican  in  the  temple  was  hardly 
anything  but  a  sigh  involuntarily  expressed,  yet  it  was  more 
pleasing  to  God  than  many  words.  But  still,  outward 
audible  words  are  of  importance,  and  react  upon  the  inward 
prayer.  Mere  internal  emotion  is  very  apt  to  fade  into 
indefiniteness,  and  to  lead  to  feebleness  in  prayer,  unless  it  is 
laid  hold  of  by  the  formative  and  practical  power  of  Christian 
will  and  thought.  When  prayer  remains  entirely  inward,  it 
is  prone  to  be  crossed  by  a  world  of  prayerless  thoughts ;  but 
when  expressed  in  words  it  draws  our  scattered  thoughts  more 
together,  and  presses  our  energies  into  its  sei'vice.  Eeal, 
audible  prayer  places  us  more  directly  in  the  act  of  prayer, 
and  by  the  mastery  we  thus  obtain  even  over  the  external 
world,  our  sacrifice  of  prayer  is  kept  from  distraction.  In 
words  prayer  attains,  as  it  were,  its  body,  its  earthly  frame. 
It  is  also  beneficial  to  set  apart  our  accustomed  place  of  prayer 
as  a  lioly  spot,  to  surround  it  as  with  a  sacred  circle,  and  thus  to 
make  it  a  templum  in  the  old  sense.     Every  study  should  be 


FORMS  OF  PRAYER,  429 

such  a  templum,  from  wliicli  we  look  out  to  lieaven  and  upon 
the  world. 

Again,  which  is  preferable — fixed  forms  of  'prayer,  or  free 
prayer  from  the  heart  ?-  The  former  have  this  disadvantage, 
that  they  allow  the  thoughts  to  wander  too  readily,  whereas 
free  prayer  brings  our  powers  much  more  into  requisition. 
Forms  of  prayer  are  also  apt  to  become  a  kind  of  mediator, 
keeping  God  and  man  apart ;  so  that  the  opiis  operatum  is 
looked  upon  as  sufiicient,  and  the  inwardness  of  immediate 
fellowship  with  God  falls  into  the  background.  Accordingly, 
spontaneous  prayer  ought  at  all  events  to  be  practised  and 
learned,  and  this  is  very  easily  done  even  by  children.  It  is 
not  difficult,  if  only  we  do  not  try,  in  the  words  we  use  in 
prayer,  to  appear  better  than  we  really  are,  but  bring 
before  God  in  a  childlike,  natural,  and  inartificial  Avay  what 
we  feel  and  what  we  long  for.  Only  we  must  not  aim  at 
speechifying,  Matt.  vi.  7  ;  on  the  contrary,  prayer  had  better 
be  short  than  too  long.  It  helps  us  to  learn  to  pray  I'rom 
the  heart  when  we  divide  our  prayer  into  thanksgiving, 
deprecation,  petition,  and  intercession  (Eieger).  Nevertheless, 
forms  of  prayer  have  also  their  own  peculiar  advantages,  and 
that  not  merely  in  times  of  dryness,  in  order  to  strengthen  and 
cultivate  within  us  the  true  sense  and  spirit  of  prayer.  Here 
we  must  again  distinguish  between  private  and  social  prayer. 
The  former  belongs  to  the  closet,  and  to  those  occasions  when 
in  the  nature  of  things  free  heart-prayer  must  prevail.  ]\Iatt. 
vi.  6.  But  since  all  association  demands  order  and  stability, 
forms  of  prayer  have  more  power  to  keep  the  individual 
members  together  than  subjective,  spontaneous  prayer.  Iix 
family  devotion,  indeed,  the  father  naturally  represents  the 
whole  family,  and  consequently  his  position  as  priest  will  find 
expression  in  free  heart-prayer  also,  which  will  take  up  all  the 
common  interests  of  the  household,  and  have  also  a  more 
stimulating  and  living  power.  The  most  suitable  counter- 
poise to  any  imperfections  that  arise  here  may  be  found  in 
conjoining  free  prayer  with  contemplation, — especially  reading 
iind  explaining  of  Scripture,  —  and  perhaps  with  sacred 
song.  But  in  pithlic  ivorship  the  prayer-book  is  to  be  pre- 
ferred. It  is  necessary  to  congregational  prayer  in  the  true 
sense,  that  the  whole  body  of  the  people  should  actually  irray, 


430  §  54.    TIMES  OF  PRAYER. 

and  not  merely  learn  God's  word  in  a  new  form.  And  sucli 
prayer  is  hardly  possible,  if  the  members  do  not  know  before- 
hand what  is  to  be  prayed,  but  are  dependent  upon  the 
clergyman,  upon  his  subjective  production  of  the  moment,  and 
liave  only  to  follow  this.  Without  a  prayer-book  all  prayer 
would  be  conducted  in  too  subjective  a  fashion,  the  churchly 
tone  would  be  lacking.  It  is  in  keeping,  therefore,  with  the 
freedom  of  the  congregation  and  the  dignity  of  public  worship, 
that  the  best  prayers  of  every  age,  which  have  been  bestowed 
upon  the  Church  in  the  course  of  her  Christian  life,  should 
be  collected  and  used.  At  the  same  time,  as  particular  and 
accidental  cases  arise,  the  gift  of  prayer  possessed  by  the 
individual  may  retain  its  place  even  in  the  church.  As  for 
the  quality  of  formularies  of  prayer,  the  Lord's  Prayer  is 
typical,  with  respect  alike  to  its  correct  estimate  of  blessings, 
its  sense  of  fellowship,  its  childlike  mood,  and — with  all  its 
brevity — its  superlative  excellence. 

§  54.    Times  of  Prayer  and  Contemplation,  or  the  Order  of  Life 
determined  hij  Christian  Piety. 

The  whole  life  of  the  Christian  must  be  a  life  of  prayer ;  and 
it  becomes  so  by  this  means  and  in  this  way — the  spirit 
of  prayer  arranges  the  life  and  divides  it  into  smaller 
and  larger  portions,  in  order  to  obtain  supremacy  over 
the  entire  lifetime.  Contemplation  and  prayer  are  works 
of  absolute  worth  in  themselves,  to  which  the  Christian 
expressly  devotes  special  seasons.  This  organization  of 
life  is  based,  in  the  narrowest  sphere  in  which  it  is 
carried  out,  upon  the  fact  that  our  physical  nature,  in 
accordance  with  a  beneficent  law  of  life,  requires  an 
alternation  of  work  and  rest,  of  daily  labour  and  recess, 
— a  law  which  is  reflected  in  the  life  of  the  spirit,  so 
that  times  in  which  we  are  engaged  with  the  duties  of 
our  calling  alternate  with  times  of  vacation,  in  order 
that  our  corporeal,  psychical,  and  spiritual  powers  may 
be  renewed  by  relaxation  and  spiritual  tranquillity. 
Accordingly,    the    Christian    spirit    of    prayer,    in    the 


TIMES  OF  PKAYEE.  431 

exercise  of  wisdom  and  discretion,  sanctions  an  order 
of  life  determined  by  Christian  piety,  in  which  our  life 
is  formed  into  an  organism  made  up  of  smaller  and 
larger  portions,  so  that  a  regular  rotation  takes  place 
which  is  indispensable  to  the  rhythm  and  harmonious 
progress  of  the  Christian  life.  These  divisions  are  in 
part  daily,  in  part  weekly  {Sunday),  and  in  part  are 
sacred  seasons  occurring  at  longer  intervals. 

The  Literature. — Cf.  the  Denlfirlirift  dcs  Emngeh  Ohcrhirch- 
enrathes  ilher  die  Sonntagsfrage,  Berlin  1877  (by  the  author). 
Calvin,  Instihctio,  ii.  c.  8.  Catechismus  Gcnev.  ad  mandatum,  iv. 
Heidelhcrger  Katceliisvius,  4  Gebot.  Conf.  Aug.  ii,  art.  7.  Katc- 
rhism.  major  Dekal.  3.  Cf.  the  works  of  Schaff',  Liebetrut, 
Sonntagsfeicr,  Kraussbold  in  Die  Zeitschrift  f.  Protest,  und 
KircJie,  1850,  p.  137  ff.  Oschwald,  Die  Sonntagsfeier,  1850. 
The  English  work,  The  Pearl  of  Days.  Hengstenberg,  Dcr 
Tag  dcs  Herrn,  1852.  Alex.  Beck,  Der  Tag  dcs  Hcrrn  und 
seine  Heiligung  Vortrag  v.  Schmid.  auf  dcm  Kirchcntag,  1850. 
Mtzsch,  Praktische  Theologie,  i.  §  56.  [Wilhelmi,  Feiertagsheils- 
gung,  1857.  Haupt,  Der  Sonntag  und  die  Bibel.  Zahn, 
Gescliichte  des  Sonntags,  1878.  Uhlhorn,  Die  Sonntagsfrage  in 
iJirer  socialen  Bedeutung,  1870.  Eieger,  Staat  und  Sonntag, 
1877.  Eohr,  Der  Sonntag  vom  socialen  und  sittlichen  Stand- 
jpunld,  1879.     Baur,  Dcr  Sonntag  und  das  Familicnledcn.'] 

1.  We  are  repeatedly  enjoined  to  pray  without  ceasing, 
Luke  xviii.  1  ;  1  Thess.  v.  17.  But  inasmuch  as  the  special 
act  of  prayer  is  not  compatible  with  every  task,  though  the 
latter  may  nevertheless  be  a  moral  duty,  such  an  injunction 
must  refer  to  the  spirit  of  prayer,  which  may  and  ought  to  be 
heard  like  an  undertone  through  all  our  work.  But  this  spirit 
of  prayer  would  soon  disappear  without  special  seasons  for 
recruiting  it.  In  the  spirit  of  prayer  we  feed  upon  the  grace 
we  have  already  received.  But  we  do  not  have  grace  at 
our  command  once  for  all ;  we  need  grace  for  grace ;  main- 
tenance and  growth,  which  here  also  are  inseparably  connected, 
demand  cessation  of  work  from  time  to  time,  that  we  may 
again  apply  to  the  fountain  of  strength.  Only  in  such  an 
alternation  as  this,  where  at  one  time  we  collect  strength  and 
at  another  exhibit  it,  can  there  be  prosperity  and  progress 
either  in  physical  or  spiritual  life,  and  accordingly  we  can 


432  §  54.    TIMES  OF  PEAYER. 

hardly  say  that  this  law  is  connected  witli  our  earthly  exist- 
ence alene.  Even  Christ  set  apart  seasons  of  prayer  for 
Himself.  But  in  the  rationale  we  have  given  it  might  appear 
as  if  work  alone  were  our  proper  aim,  and  prayer  only  the 
means  of  supplying  ns  with  the  power  to  perform  it,  as  if 
prayer  were  therefore  only  a  means  of  virtue,  and  the  amount 
of  time  to  be  given  up  to  it  had  to  be  determined  by  work, 
which  is  the  real  aim.  This  standpoint,  however,  is  altogether 
false.  Prayer  and  contemplation  are  in  themselves  ethical  acts, 
ends  in  themselves,  and  of  absolute  worth.  As  the  Triune 
God  is  an  objective  Good  in  Himself,  and  not  merely  by 
reason  of  His  works,  so,  too,  our  action  has  an  absolute  moral 
value  when  we  are  directly  occupied  with  God,  and  not  merely 
when  we  are  occupied  with  individual  moral  relations.  Nay, 
such  action  is  the  centre  of  all  action,  as  it  refers  to  the  moral 
centre  of  the  world,  to  God  in  Christ.  It  is  a  divine  work, 
and  communion  with  God,  which  it  enables  ns  constantly  to 
realize  afresh,  is  an  independent  good  in  itself,  which  can  only 
subsist  by  being  continually  renewed.  Since  prayer  and 
contemplation  are  central,  they  are  regulative ;  appointing 
their  times  to  all  our  tasks  by  quickening  the  sense  of  God 
within  ns ;  and  thereby  most  surely  enabling  us  to  set  about 
our  work  in  the  right  spirit.  There  must  therefore  be  special 
times  of  jyrayer  in  the  Christian  life.  Not  as  if  these  alone 
were  divine,  sacred,  and  religious,  and  times  of  work  pro- 
fane, but  quite  the  reverse.  Their  object  is  that  no  moment 
may  be  left  profane,  without  God,  or  irreligious,  but  rather 
that  everything  may  conduce  to  quicken  the  Christian's  sense 
of  God,  to  keep  the  spirit  of  prayer  in  constant  activity,  and 
to  teach  us  to  discover  in  everything  the  side  which  connects 
it  with  God,  in  other  words,  to  view  and  treat  everything  in 
the  divine  light. 

2.  Many,  liowever,  resist  a  fixed  order.  They  liold  that 
it  should  be  left  to  the  free  sjDiritual  impulse  of  the  moment 
to  determine  when  a  time  should  be  set  apart  for  prayer  and 
contemplation  ;  that  only  in  this  way  can  prayer  have  inward 
truthfulness,  and  only  thus  can  we  be  delivered  from  a  new 
spirit  of  legalism.  But,  with  regard  to  the  individual  life, 
this  would  mean,  either  that  in  the  life  of  the  believer 
times    of   slothfulness   never  occurred,   or   else   that   he   can 


A  FIXED  OEDER  IN  PEAYEE.  433 

do  nothing  against  them,  but  only  wait  until  the  spiritual 
impulse  returns.  This  would  be  mere  passive  resignation,  the 
ethics  of  Mohammedanism.  But,  as  we  have  already  seen 
(§  48),  self-discipline  has  a  part  to  play  in  the  life  of  the 
Christian.  And  as  far  as  the  fear  of  legalism  is  concerned,  it  is 
only  necessary  that  it  should  be  the  spirit  itself  which  wills  and 
arranges  the  order,  that  it  should  do  so  freely,  recognising 
it  to  be  something  good,  and  adhere  to  it  as  a  means  of 
resisting  the  ilesh,  which  ought  to  be  disciplined  and  held  in 
subjection  by  the  spirit,  until  perhaps  Christian  wisdom  per- 
ceives that  the  necessities  of  the  case  have  altered.  If 
this  order  be  fixed  by  the  Christian  spirit  in  prospective 
wisdom,  there  is  nothing  arbitrary  about  it.  There  would 
rather  be  arbitrariness  where  there  was  no  order,  and  it  would 
be  unethical  to  leave  the  maintenance  of  a  right  inward  state 
of  heart  to  the  mercy  of  accident.  Christian  freedom  is  not 
disorder  nor  monotony,  but  a  freedom  duly  organized,  and  the 
new  man  is  sustained  by  establishing  a  definite  order,  and 
adhering  to  it.  Hence  the  striking  saying  of  Augustine : 
"  Keep  order,  and  it  will  keep  thee."  The  only  thing 
required,  therefore,  is  that  the  believer  should  either,  in 
the  exercise  of  his  own  wisdom,  form  a  fixed  order  for 
liimself  according  to  his  needs,  or  should  fall  in  with  that 
which  already  exists,  and  there  walk  at  liberty.  It  is  impos- 
sible to  see  why  in  every  other  instance  the  regulation  of  the 
practical  work  of  love  should  be  regarded,  not  as  hampering 
the  exercise  of  freedom,  but  as  promoting  it,  while  in  the  work 
of  contemplation  and  prayer  alone — a  work,  too,  of  absolute 
ethical  value — order  and  freedom  should  be  looked  upon  as 
incompatible,  and  even  contradictory.  Further,  in  the 
practice  of  piety  the  life  of  the  believer  ought  not  to  remain 
an  isolated  one,  but  to  embody  in  itself  the  generic  conscious- 
ness. Thus  individual  'piety  demands  also  association  in  the 
worshijj  of  God,  and  is  raised  and  stimulated  by  it.  This 
must  be  taken  into  account  by  Christian  wisdom  when  insti- 
tuting a  pious  order  of  life  ;  otherwise,  by  falling  into  separation, 
it  undervalues  the  blessing  to  be  derived  from  the  spirit  of 
fellowship,  and  the  essentially  organic  position  which  the 
individual  holds.  And  now,  should  a  common  order  of  pious 
duties  be  established,  ix.  an  orde^-  of  life  for  the  Christian 

2  E 


434  §  54.  TIMES  OF  PRAYER. 

community,  the  individual  must  also  shape  the  order  of  his  ] 
own  religious  life  so  as  to  he  in  harmony  with  it,  so  as  to 
promote  and  not  to  hinder  it.  This  last  consideration  is  of 
more  importance  for  the  longer,  regularly  recurring  portions  of 
time  set  apart  for  prayer  and  contemplation,  while  for  the 
shorter  ones  that  occur  each  day  it  is  sufficient  to  take  into 
account  the  necessities  of  the  individual  life.  But  such  a 
division  of  our  time,  both  into  longer  and  shorter  portions, 
is  only  possible  if  men  are  not  so  constituted  that  each  one 
must,  in  order  to  have  a  right  order  for  himself,  have  one 
different  from  that  of  everybody  else ;  that  is  to  say,  only  if 
there  is  a  univcrscd  law  of  life,  in  human  nature,  the  same  for 
every  one,  upon  which  to  base  the  regulation  of  our  life, — a 
law  that  demands  pauses  in  our  work,  points  of  rest,  without 
which  human  life  would  fall  into  mere  mechanism. 

3.  Now,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  the  essential  identity  of 
humanity  does  not  merely  go  the  length  of  making  all  men 
stand  in  need  of  such  a  pious  ordering  of  life.  It  goes 
farther  than  this ;  so  that  three  circles  of  religious  duties, 
each  exceeding  the  other,  and  expressing  the  form  which  the 
regulation  of  Christian  freedom  takes,  may  be  described. 

The  first  of  these  especially,  but  also  the  second,  depends 
upon  the  laws  of  terrestrial  life ;  the  third  arises  more 
immediately  from  the  necessities  or  laws  of  spiritual  life 
alone. 

{a)  The  first  is  that  of  daily  life.  Daily  life,  from  the 
general  conditions  of  earthly  existence,  is  divided  into  waking 
and  sleeping.  When  we  awake  we  naturally  first  of  all  look 
upward  and  give  thanks,  then  we  look  forward  into  the 
day,  survey  the  duties  that  lie  before  us,  make  our  plans  as 
to  how  we  shall  spend  our  time,  what  tasks  we  must  engage 
in  and  in  what  order,  and  for  the  accomplishment  of  these 
seek  strength  and  calmness  in  God.  In  the  evening  we  look 
just  us  naturally  backward,  in  order  to  regain  the  harmony  we 
have  lost,  and  to  give  ourselves  to  rest  in  renewed  assurance 
of  reconciliation  with  God ;  and  in  general,  to  bring  the  past 
to  mind,  and  appropriate  its  blessing  for  the  present.  For 
that  man  is  frivolous  and  undervalues  the  leadings  of  God  in 
sorrow  and  joy,  whose  efforts  are  all  directed  to  the  future, 
and  who  never  collects  his  thoughts  to  look  back  upon  what 


SUNDAY.  435 

liG  has  lived  through  in  the  past.  The  outcome  of  such  efforts 
and  such  work  is  mere  restless  movement,  it  is  not  real  gain 
nor  progress.^  Time  is  a  capital  entrusted  to  us  by  God,  a 
capital  that  consists  not  merely  of  the  present  or  the  uncertain 
future,  but  also  of  the  past,  which  is  meant  to  live  on  in 
the  present  in  the  form  of  remembrance ;  and  the  more  we 
iniT'posdy  attach  importance  to  the  past,  the  more  faithful 
will  memory  become.  If,  then,  in  the  evening  it  is  the  past 
that  is  naturally  uppermost  in  our  mind,  in  the  morning  the 
future,  while  during  our  day's  work  it  is  the  present — we 
may  say  that  in  the  morning  piety  appears  as  lioipe,  arising 
from  faith,  that  love,  has  to  inspire  our  daily  work,  and  that 
in  the  evening  piety  comes  back  from  work  to  the  rest  of 
faith  in  God, 

During  the  day,  too,  certain  natural  pauses  occur,  in  which 
the  physical  life  recovers  its  strength,  and  in  these  it  is  a 
good  and  salutary  thing  to  restore  the  balance  between  the 
sensuous  and  the  spiritual  side  of  our  nature,  by  lifting  our 
souls  to  the  Giver  of  bodily  strength.  Besides,  thankfulness 
requires  this  at  our  hands  {vicl.  sup.  p.  427).  This  is  the  first 
circle  of  pious  duties,  and  a  fundamental  one  for  the  individual 
life  and  for  the  Christian  character  of  family  life.  And  it  is 
not  difficult  to  observe  these  home  religious  duties. 

(b)  It  is  not  so  easy  to  construct  the  second  circle,  that,  viz.,  of 
wechly  religious  duties.  Here  the  Sunday  question  is  involved. 
Within  the  last  ten  years  this  question  has  been  discussed 
in  many  and  various  ways,  as  indeed  it  deserves  to  be, 
from  its  importance  for  individual  and  national  life.  A 
whole  literature  has  been  formed  in  connection  with  it.  In 
addition  to  the  articles  already  mentioned  by  Oschwald, 
Liebetrut,  Kraussold,  Schaff,  etc.,  the  Proceedings  of  the  Stutt- 
gart Church  Diet,  1850,  are  worthy  of  notice.  These  contain 
a  striking  address  by  Dr.  Schmid,  in  which  he  shows  at 
length  how  at  present  the  Sunday  has  almost  become  the 
most  occupied  day  in  the  week,  whether  as  regards  work,  or 
amusement,  or  even  debauchery.  Things  have  come  to  such 
a  pass  that,  according  to  statistics,  most  crimes  are  committed 
on  Sunday ;  that  it  strengthens  the  secular  spirit,  and  instead 

1  Hence  it  is  right  even  to  set  apart  days  to  commemorate  important  events 
in  onr  own  life  and  in  the  lives  of  onr  friends. 


436  §  54.  TIMES  OF  PEAYEK. 

of  seasoning  and  consecrating  the  national  life,  has  rathet 
become  a  pest  within  it.  .  Various  causes  are  assigned  for 
this  by  Schmid.  One  of  these  is  a  false  Evangelicalism, 
tending  to  antinomianism  ;  others  are  that  men  are  gradually 
ceasing  to  feel  the  need  of  intercourse  with  God  in  prayer ; 
that  the  ttudy  of  the  Bible  is  put  low  in  the  scale  of 
importance,  as,  for  example,  in  the  spiritualistic  delusion  that 
he  who  has  once  become  a  Christian  finds  everything  already 
given  in  his  Christian  consciousness,  and  does  not  require,  for 
his  growth,  that  word  of  God  through  which  he  became  a 
Christian  at  first ;  and,  finally,  that  the  ties  of  domestic  and 
church  fellowship  are  being  relaxed.  If  the  members  of  a 
Christian  family  were  as  heartily  united  as  they  ought  to  be, 
they  would  eagerly  welcome  those  still  hours  which  Sunday 
affords,  free  from  the  stress  of  everyday  business  life,  in 
order  to  give  to  education  its  true  intellectual  and  spiritual 
centre  in  the  family,  and  to  bring  down  a  Sabbath  blessing 
upon  family  life.  In  like  manner,  too,  if  Christian  life  had 
less  of  an  individualistic  and  more  of  a  common  spirit,  the 
need  of  joining  in  congregational  worship  would  be  more 
generally  felt,  both  for  our  own  good  and  that  of  others. 
Nitzsch  says  (PraU.  Theol.  i.  §  56,  p.  345  sq.),  "  If  the 
distinction  between  work  days  and  holy  days  were  abolished, 
and  work  as  well  as  worship  were  left  to  any  day  that  each 
one  might  choose,  the  result  would  be  the  dissolution  of  the 
Church." 

What  has  been  said  might  be  of  itself  sufficient  to  commend 
the  Christian  observance  of  Sunday,  which,  as  is  shown  in 
the  case  of  Great  Britain,  is  favourable  both  to  the  intellectual 
and  economical  welfare  of  the  people  at  large,  and  especially 
of  the  lower  classes,  and  in  which  more  than  in  anything  else 
a  people  can  manifest  its  Christian  life. 

In  the  ancient  Church  some  Christians  kept  Sunday  as  the 
day  of  the  resurrection  ;  others,  according  to  Ignatius,  held  fast 
to  the  Sabbath ;  while  others,  again,  kept  both  days.  The 
Confcssio  Augustana  rests  the  Sabbath  almost  entirely  upon 
the  fact,  that  people  must  agree  as  to  a  day  for  the  common 
worship  of  God,  and  the  Catcchismus  major  does  not  advance 
beyond  this  point  of  view  in  any  essential  respect.  At  the 
Reformation  the  Lutheran  and  Eeformed   Churches   (Calvin, 


SUNDAY.  437 

Iiistitutio,  ii.  c.  8.  Heidelberg  Catechism.  Fourth  Command- 
ment), in  opposition  to  spiritual  legalism,  laid  special  emphasis 
in  this  connection  upon  evangelical  liberty,  on  the  ground  that 
a  little  leaven  might  leaven  the  whole  lump.  Still  a  fixed 
rule  for  the  observance  of  Sunday,  which  the  Christian  spirit 
freely  makes  for  itself,  is  quite  consistent  with  Christian 
liberty,  and  we  are  indebted  to  the  Puritans  and  the  Scotch 
for  having  been  the  first  to  direct  attention  to  this  matter. 
However  much  the  Puritan  movement,  which  spread  like  a 
flood  over  the  whole  of  Great  Britain,  afterwards  retreated 
within  more  moderate  limits,  the  introduction  of  a  settled 
Sunday  observance,  dating  from  that  time,  has  proved  a 
blessing  to  the  whole  national  life  of  England  and  Scotland,  a 
blessing  which  later  ages  have  not  allowed  to  be  taken  from 
them,  and  which,  transferred  to  North  America,  has  become  an 
essential  condition  of  the  spiritual  health  of  the  nation.  For 
in  these  busy  commercial  countries,  with  their  artisan  and 
manufacturing  populations,  the  Sunday  is  tlie  power  which 
maintains  the  balance  between  the  inner  life  and  its  nurture 
and  the  restless  outward  life.  It  was  a  sound  instinct  which, 
soon  after  Elizabeth's  time,  demanded  the  Sunday  as  the 
regulator  of  the  whole  national  life,  and  has  hitherto  main- 
tained it  as  such  :  for  without  fixed  rules  for  Sunday  observ- 
ance, these  nations  would  have  been  liable  to  be  swallowed  up 
in  the  mechanism  or  materialism  of  work,  and  thus  a  large 
portion  of  the  population  would  have  been  degraded  to  the 
position  of  Helots,  while  the  remaining  portion  would  have  lost 
much  of  the  ideal  import  of  life.  It  may  be  said  in  general 
that  the  English  Sunday  is  the  foundation  of  English  freedom ; 
it  is  the  subjection  of  time  to  the  ordinance  of  God,  and  this 
acts  as  a  pattern  for  bringing  the  national  life  in  general  into 
subjection  to  God's  ordinances  and  laws.  And  it  is  only  when 
rooted  in  the  soil  of  law  that  freedom  can  flourish.  The 
history  of  Germany  has  hitherto  been  a  different  one.  The 
German  people  as  a  whole  did  not  run  so  much  risk  from  the 
tendency  to  mere  mechanism  ;  they  have  been  for  the  most 
part  an  agricultural  race.  From  their  habit  of  mind,  too,  con- 
templation, even  during  the  week,  occupies  a  larger  place  in 
their  life  than  it  does  in  the  case  of  the  nations  we  have  men- 
tioned, and  by  this  means  elements  of  Sabbath-life  are  inter- 


438  §  51.  TIMES  OF  PRAYER. 

woven  with  the  week  days.  Still  this  is  not  enough  to  render 
Sunday  unnecessary.  With  reference  to  commerce  and  manu- 
factures, a  state  of  things  is  being  developed  amongst  ourselves 
which  is  already  analogous  to  what  exists  in  these  nations. 
For  one  thing,  family  worship  has,  to  a  large  extent,  to  be  set 
up  over  again  in  Germany  as  a  customary  practice.  Still,  the 
individuality  of  the  German  race  will  have  to  be  taken  into 
account  when  we  contemplate  the  necessary  improvement  of 
our  observance  of  Sunday,  a  work  which  will  be  of  the  greatest 
importance  to  the  energy  of  our  national  life  as  well  as  to 
our  self-respect  as  a  Christian  people.  And  in  many  ways  our 
age  is  favourable  to  such  an  improvement.  Our  workmen  and 
day-labourers  are  already  making  their  voices  heard  with  ever 
increasing  strength,  both  in  the  towns  and — to  some  extent — in 
the  country,  demanding  that  a  Sunday  should  be  given  them ; 
and  this  is  no  wonder.  We  here  see  the  harmony  that  subsists 
between  God's  ordinance  and  man's  natural  requirements,  for, 
even  according  to  a  wholly  worldly  standard,  it  is  reasonable 
and  advantageous  that  man  should  have  a  Sunday,  it  is  a  free- 
dom to  which  he  is  entitled  to  have  a  free  day ;  and  when  once 
he  has  secured  it,  it  will  be  the  duty  of  the  Church  to  redouble 
its  zeal,  and  see  that  it  is  worthily  employed. 

Foundation  of  the  Christian  Sunday.  The  observance  of 
Sunday  cannot  be  based  upon  the  Mosaic  law  by  itself.  For 
in  that  case  the  Sabbath,  the  seventh  day,  would  have  to  be 
made  the  day  of  rest  instead  of  the  first.  And  the  legal  penal 
sanctions  which  were  given  in  connection  with  the  Sabbath 
would  also  be  still  in  force.  Christ  Himself  took  up  a  free 
position  towards  the  Sabbath.  My  Father  worketh  even  until 
now,  and  I  work  (John  v.  17).  To  the  same  effect  is  Mark  ii. 
27,  the  Sabbath  was  made  for  man.  Similarly,  Paul  (Eom. 
xiv.  5  ;  Col.  ii.  16  f,)  enjoins  Christians  not  to  make  it  a 
matter  of  conscience  to  keep  new  moons,  Sabbath  days,  etc., — 
that  is,  not  to  regard  the  Jewish  observance  of  holy  days  as 
indispensable.  He  wishes  the  whole  life  to  be  holy  and  con- 
secrated to  God.  Nevertheless  he  nowhere  says  that  it  is 
morally  wrong  to  set  apart  special  times  for  collecting  and 
recruiting  our  energies.  On  the  contrary,  he  recommends 
self-examination  (1  Cor.  xi.).  Further,  he  directs  collections 
to  be  made  anion"-  the  Corinthian  Christians  at  their  regular 


FOUNDATION  OF  THE  CHEISTIAN  SUNDAY.  439 

weekly  gatherings  (1  Cor.  xvi.  2);^  and  Christ  Himself  not 
only  assumes,  without  a  word  of  blame,  the  continuance  of  the 
Sabbath  by  His  disciples  (Matt.  xxiv.  20),  but  also  says — the 
day  of  rest  was  made  for  man.  Accordingly,  that  which  is 
abolished  is  looking  upon  the  Sabbath  as  something  rendered  to 
God,  as  an  offering  of  time.  But  here  too  the  saying  applies, 
that  from  the  beginning  it  was  not  so.  On  the  contrary,  it 
was  instituted,  according  to  Gen.  ii.  1-3,  as  a  day  of  blessing, 
a  gift  which  God  Himself  has  sanctified ;  and  prophecy 
already  to  some  extent  again  conceived  of  it  in  this  way :  it  is 
tlie  day  which  is  to  be  kept  holy  as  a  blessing  to  man  (Ezek. 
XX.  12,  20,  xxii.  8,  26  ;  Isa.  Ivi.  6).  To  this  beginning  the 
gospel  returns,  setting  forth,  as  the  fundamental  idea  of  the 
Sabbath,  rest  in  God, — that  supreme  good  which  was  sought 
after  under  Old  Testament  forms  and  in  Old  Testament  times, 
but  was  not  found  until  Christianity  appeared  (Heb.  iv.), — a 
rest,  indeed,  in  which  the  whole  life  is  to  have  its  share.  This 
end  is  attained  by  having  fixed  seasons  for  collecting  our 
thoughts  and  raising  them  to  God,  and  by  both  public  and 
family  edification.  Sunday  is  not  given  for  idleness.  No 
part  of  life  is  to  be  devoted  to  sloth.  The  Old  Testament 
Sabbath  is  a  creation- festival,  designed  for  bodily  rest  and 
relaxation,  but  also  for  spiritual  strengthening ;  for  it  is  to  be 
kept  holy.  In  the  New  Testament  it  is  at  the  same  time  a 
memorial  of  Christ's  resurrection  as  the  sign  of  the  new 
creation.^  But  the  institution  of  the  Sabbath  (Gen.  ii.)  has  a 
permanent  significance.  It  expresses,  namely,  that  this  peri- 
odical recurrence  of  pauses  is  a  law  of  life  implanted  by  the 
Creator,^  and  must  be  kept  sacred  like  other  natural  laws 
implanted  by  Him — as,  e.g.,  the  regular  alternation  of  sleep 
and  waking  hours.  The  order  of  nature  is  no  less  an 
expression  of  the  divine  will  than  the  positive  divine  law; 
just  as  the  State,  for  instance,  is  a  divine  ordinance,  without 
its  being  established  by  a  positive  law  of  God. 

^  Kara  fji.iav  ffa,p,^a.Tuv,  i.e.  on  the  first  day  of  the  week,  which  was  therefore  the 
day  for  assemblies. 

-  It  is  called  y.-jpiayJ,,  the  Lord's  day,  and  was  at  first  kept  as  a  Christian  holy 
day  along  with  the  Sabbath,  but  soon  afterwards  instead  of  it. 

*  At  the  French  Revolution  the  tenth  day  was  tried ;  but  the  attempt  only 
served  to  prove  that  in  the  old  custom  there  was  a  true  perception  of  natural  law, 
and  accordingly  it  was  soon  reverted  to. 


440  §  .54.  TIMES  OF  PKAYER. 

With  regard  to  the  eynployment  of  the  day  of  rest,  the  OhI 
Testament  gave  but  few  definite  directions.  Abstention  from 
everyday  work  leaves  hours  of  life  disposable  at  once  for 
l)odily  relaxation  and  physical  refreshment.  No  time  must  be 
devoted  to  actual  idleness,  but  it  may  be  devoted  to  the 
restoration  of  the  physical  powers,  and  to  means  suitable  for 
this  purpose.  Even  in  Old  Testament  times  the  Sabbath  was 
a  day  of  joy.  It  is  wrong  to  ignore  this  aspect  of  Sunday, 
and  to  hold  that  the  enjoyment  of  nature  and  social  inter- 
course ought  to  be  avoided.  At  the  same  time,  a  relaxation 
that  means  fresh  excitement,  a  rest  that  only  brings  unrest 
and  fatigue,  friction  and  not  recreation,  cannot  be  defended  on 
ethical  principles.  But  the  most  important  thing  is  mental 
recreation  and  refreshment,  and  of  these  the  most  active  source 
and  centre  is  the  rest  in  God  that  is  found  in  family  and 
public  edification.  The  prophets  show  that  the  Sabbath  is 
not  kept  holy  by  doing  nothing,  but,  in  particular,  by  the 
worship  of  God  (Ezek.  xx.  12,  20,  xxii.  8,  26;  Isa.  Ivi.  6). 
In  the  time  of  Christ,  Sabbath-day  divine  service  was  already 
prevalent.  Eeligious  work  must  be  the  regulator  of  this  day. 
The  contemplation  of  the  fieyaXeia  Oeov,  the  raising  of  the  soul 
above  time  to  eternity — this  is  the  most  worthy  employment 
of  Sunday.  Further,  the  Christian  Sunday  has  been  given  us 
for  visiting  and  comforting  the  poor,  the  sick,  the  prisoners, 
and  for  works  of  Christian  love  in  general, — for  all  that  is 
comprehended  under  the  name  of  home  mission  work,  and 
which  lies  outside  the  ordinary  duties  of  our  vocation. 
Schleiermacher  ^  has  shown  how  such  works  are  necessary 
alongside  of  our  special  vocation,  since  they  refresh  our 
business  life  and  preserve  it  from  mechanism.  The  full 
ideal  of  Sunday  does  not  lie  in  discontinuance  of  the  Sabbath, 
but  in  the  whole  life  being  sustained  by  rest  in  God,  as  we 
see  the  life  of  Christ  to  have  been  (John  v.  17).  But  we 
shall  attain  this  end  all  the  more  surely,  the  more  we  grant 
that  it  is  right  to  have  a  fixed  order  of  Sunday  observance,  and 
the  more  we  arrange  one  in  such  a  way  as  Christian  love  and 
wisdom  may  require. 

(c)  Finally,  a  third  circle  is  formed  by  times  in  ivhich  we 
look  backward  or  forward,  and  into  our  own  hearts,  times  of 

^  Chrislliche  Sille,  p.  154  sq. 


§  5.5.  CIieiSTIAN  EELIGIOUS  ZEAL.  441 

comprehensive  periodical  recollection  and  invigoration.  In 
many  respects  we  cannot  be  conscious  of  our  backsliding  or 
our  progress  after  days  or  short  intervals.  But  it  is  needful 
for  the  new  man  to  survey,  from  time  to  time,  his  spiritual  con- 
dition as  a  whole,  and  to  pass  judgment  upon  himself ;  and  then 
ail  that  is  defective  in  him,  and  which  in  its  separate  items 
escaped  his  notice,  is  seen  in  its  connection  and  significance. 
Such  times  of  self-examination,  moreover,  will  always  make 
us  sensible  of  our  special  need  of  comfort  and  strength,  to 
enable  us  to  carry  out  the  life-resolves  whicli  we  form  anew. 
Hence  they  will  lead  the  Christian  to  the  feast  which  Christ 
has  instituted  for  this  very  purpose,  that  He  may  slay  death 
in  us  by  His  own  death,  that  we  may  find  life  in  Him. 

Note. — The  second  and  tliird  circles  have  already  directed  our 
attention  from  private  to  social  piety  ;  contemplation  and  prayer 
must  be  engaged  in  along  with  others.  By  this  means  the 
Christian  generic  consciousness  is  brought  into  association  with 
these  religious  exercises,  and  this  is  of  great  importance  to  its 
development. 

§  55.    Christicai  Religious  Zeal. 

We  have  seen  that  prayer  is  at  least  an  inward  exercise  of 
piety.  Now,  the  outward  expression  that  is  given  to 
the  inward  act  is  not  the  precise  end  that  is  contem- 
plated ;  it  is  more  in  the  nature  of  an  accidental  and 
involuntary  accompaniment.  Piety,  liowever,  seeks  also 
an  effectual  and  intended  manifestation  in  the  form  of 
religious  zeal,  which  shows  itself  on  the  one  hand  in 
confession  of  the  truth  (6/xo\oyia,  ^aprvpla,  witness- 
bearing),  and  on  the  other  in  the  2^'>'Oclamation  of  it 
(Krjpvyfia).  Thus  the  common  object  of  both  is  Chris- 
tian truth.  The  fundamental  moral  quality,  however, 
that  characterizes  confession  is  truthfulness,  which,  by 
rejecting  temptations  to  deny  Christ  in  speech  or  act, 
or  by  undutiful  silence,  evinces  and  displays  conscien- 
tious fidelity  towards  itself  and  towards  Christ,  and 
shows  that  it  esteems  the  good  of  fellowship  with  Him 
to  be  higher  than  any  other  good.      On  the  other  hand, 


442  §  55.  CIIItlSTIAN  RELIGIOUS  ZEAL. 

love  is  the  standard  in  the  lorodamation  of  the  truth  ; 
love,  which  asserts  the  truth  not  only  as  something 
l)elonging  to  itself,  but  also  as  belonging  to  others,  and 
therefore  makes  others  its  object. 

Schleiermacher,  Christliche  Sitte,  p.  580  ff.  Cf.  Eothe,  I.e. 
1st  ed.  iii.  §  997. 

Note. — It  is  true  that  confession  and  martyrdom  include  a 
reference  to  others.  For  part  of  their  purpose  is  to  make 
manifest,  for  the  sake  of  others,  the  sincerity  of  the  inward 
conviction.  But  this  is  only  done  in  order  that  fidelity  in 
faith  may  be  shown  to  be  a  matter  of  duty — that  is,  a  duty  to 
God  and  to  oneself.  In  the  proclamation  of  truth,  on  the  other 
liand,  which  accordingly  belongs  to  the  social  sphere,  we  make 
our  fellow-men  our  first  aim. 

1.  The  Christian  makes  no  secret  of  his  own  faith,  for  he 
knows  that  Christianity  is  not  merely  a  private  matter  or 
possession  of  his  own,  but  a  salt,  a  light  for  the  world.  Out 
of  the  abundance  of  the  heart  the  mouth  speaketh,  Matt.  xii. 
34  ff.  If  we  confess  with  the  mouth  the  faith,  namely,  which 
is  in  us,  Eora.  x.  10,  we  shall  be  saved  through  such  faith 
courageously  asserting  itself  in  confession.  The  Christian 
seeks  to  make  his  whole  life  a  confession  of  gratitude,  Koni. 
xii.  1.  To  deny  Christ  would  be  to  Him  shameless  ingrati- 
tude, infidelity  towards  his  most  faithful  friend,  Mark  xiv. 
29  f . ;  Luke  ix.  26,  xxii.  34.  The  Christian,  therefore,  is 
not  afraid  of  letting  his  whole  being  bear  the  Christian 
stamp,  in  intercourse  with  others,  in  tone  and  bearing,  in 
dress  and  speech,  etc.  In  all  these  confession  is  made.  Here 
several  duties  are  still  in  the  background ;  although  love  to 
God  in  Christ  is  the  soul  of  all  we  do,  nevertheless  our 
relations  to  our  fellow-men  do  not  supply  our  chief,  our  most 
immediate  aim.  And  yet  we  do  not  act  without  a  purpose. 
Our  purpose  is  to  assert  our  union  with  God  in  Christ,  and 
to  assert  by  truthfulness  our  Christian  self  -  identity.  In 
confession  the  Christian  is  actuated  by  the  inner  necessity 
alone,  of  not  denying  outwardly  what  he  is  inwardly.  How 
different  confession  is  from  proclamation  of  the  truth  (the 
means  of  giving  it  currency)  may  be  seen  especially  from  the 
fact,  that  in  the  latter  we  have  to  proclaim  something  that 
is  much  better  than  ourselves,  for  then  we  are  preaching  to 


CONFESSION  OF  CHRISTIAN  FAITH.  443 

ourselves  as  well  as  to  others.  But  confession,  which  reaches 
its  culmination  in  martyrdom,  is  a  declaration  as  to  our 
personal  position  in  the  matter.  Here  it  is  not  only  objec- 
tive truth  that  is  required,  but  personal  truthfulness.  We 
must  not,  however,  allow  any  self-importance  to  be  mixed  up 
with  this  personal  element.  Christianity  does  not  depend 
upon  us ;  we  must  not  take  pleasure  in  a  zeal  for  confession 
that  has  its  roots  in  vanity  and  pride,  and  which  would 
therefore  be  impure — nay,  a  lie  before  God.  In  such  a 
personal  matter  as  this  we  must  act  with  modesty.  J.  J. 
Eambach  says  with  truth,  "  Confession  for  its  own  sake  is 
nothing  but  leaves,  it  is  blossom  and  fruit  that  are  of  value." 
And  yet  even  an  unseasonable  confession  of  Christian  truth. 
Matt.  vii.  4,  when  it  threatens  to  involve  us  in  injury  and 
danger,  is  more  honourable,  because  it  costs  self-denial,  than 
one  which  promises  to  be  to  our  advantage.  Confession  may 
become  fashionable ;  but  wherever  it  is  the  fashion,  there 
indeed  we  need  fear  no  martyrdom  for  confessors,  but  we 
may  very  well  apprehend  harm  to  their  souls.  This  is  the 
time  for  honest  Christians  to  evince  the  self-denial  that  ought 
to  be  found  in  those  who  make  confession  of  Christ,  by 
testifying  against  mere  fashionable  virtue,  by  bearing  witness 
that  living  faith  must  precede  confession,  that  truthfulness 
is  the  life  of  confession,  and  that  there  can  be  no  faith 
without  humility  and  spiritual  modesty.  The  Christian  will 
not  seek  for  opportunities  of  speaking  about  himself  and  his 
(jwn  faith ;  but  he  will  certainly  seek  for  opportunities  of 
making  the  trutli  hnoivn  to  others.  And  this  he  can  do  by 
word  or  deed ;  for  it  is  not  the  function  of  a  special  order 
only.  The  Christian  waits  until  the  duty  of  personal  con- 
fession— i.e.  confession  of  his  own  personal  position  with 
regard  to  Christian  truth — is  laid  upon  him  as  a  duty  by  his 
Christian  profession ;  until  he  is  placed  in  the  status  con- 
fcssionis — i.e.  until  silence  would  mean  indifference  to  truth, 
or  positive  denial  of  it,  or  consent  to  its  denial.  Then,  indeed, 
lie  boldly  makes  confession.  It  would  be  a  false  thing  to  be 
willing  to  appear  worse,  more  unbelieving  than  we  really  are ; 
it  would  be  ingratitude  to  Christ,  whose  kingdom  is  increased 
by  such  acts  of  courageous  confession  as  spring  from  our 
Christian    standing    and    involve    self-denial.      But   altlioush 


444  §  55.  CHRISTIAN  RELIGIOUS  ZEAL. 

truthfulness  is  the  soul  of  confession,  yet  this  trutlifulness 
is  not  severed  from  love.  There  is  nothing  heartless,  nothing 
of  the  judge,  nothing  defiant  about  the  Christian,  not  even  in 
his  confession,  Jas.  iv.  2  ;  Matt.  vii.  1  ff.  Confession  may, 
indeed,  have  the  result  of  bringing  about  a  definite  verdict 
and  a  separation,  but  it  must  not  seek  to  assume  the  character 
of  a  judgment.  It  is  all  the  more  irresistible,  the  more  it  is 
seen  to  be  an  imperative  act  of  conscience  prompted  by  our 
Christian  profession,  the  more  it  is  evident  that  for  God  as 
the  highest  Good  of  the  soul  we  are  willing  to  give  up 
everything  else,  the  more  our  words  and  demeanour  make 
it  manifest  that  our  sincere  wish  is  to  make  others  parti- 
cipators with  ourselves  in  Christian  salvation,  its  peace  and 
its  joy,  and  not  merely  to  impose  faith  upon  them  as  a  duty. 
This  is  the  spirit  also  of  true  martyrdom,  of  which  Christ  is 
to  us  the  pattern.  That  man  will  be  the  first  to  become 
like  Christ  who  is  afraid  lest  he  may  not  stand  the  test. 
Obstinate  self-confidence  has  already  fallen,  Luke  xxii.  34. 
St.  Paul  is  an  illustration  of  how  love  is  included  in  the 
martyr-spirit  of  the  Christian,  Acts  xxvi.  29  :  "I  would  thou 
wert  such  as  I  am,  except  these  bonds."  In  proclamation 
of  the  truth,  on  the  contrary,  which  is  an  influence  brought 
to  bear  upon  others,  we  seek  opportunities  unweariedly  and 
with  the  inventiveness  of  love.  This  subject  belongs  to  the 
chapter  on  Social  Love. 

2.  The  inward  limit  of  religious  zeal  as  onanifestccl  in 
confession  is  love.  Its  relation  to  the  various  Christian 
confessions  is  determined  by  the  principle — Christ  the  common 
faith  of  believers  is  above  every  particular  system  of  faith.  To 
reverse  this  order  is  sectarianism,  bigotry.  At  the  same  time. 
Christian  tolerance  is  no  less  distinct  from  indifferentism. 
Fanaticism  is  the  passionate,  and  therefore  egoistic  endeavour 
to  make  the  divine  a  power  in  the  world — the  divine,  that  is, 
according  to  one's  own  conception  of  it.  In  this  sense 
fanaticism  is  common  to  all  pre-Christian  stages  of  religion, 
so  far  as  they  are  not  indifferent  but  zealous ;  for  they  seek 
to  uphold  the  Divine,  and  maintain  its  glory  by  means  of  the 
State ;  as  yet  perfect  faith  in  the  power  of  the  Divine  is 
lacking,  nor  is  the  necessity  of  a  free  process  as  yet  recog- 
nised.    With  the  fanatic  everything  depends  upon  submission 


§  56.  THE  NEW  PERSONALITY  IN  RELATION  TO  ITSELF.       445 

to  the  religions  tenets  which  he  favours.  He  is  all  the  while 
unconscious  of  the  fact  that  such  submission  is  not  religion — 
nay,  that  real  religion  is  not  as  yet  in  his  own  heart,  however 
much  he  may  think  so.^  Hence  fanaticism  is  akin  to  hypo- 
crisy. Mere  objective  religious  zeal  for  the  constitution  or 
dogmas  of  the  Christian  Church  is  not  yet  religious  zeal  in 
the  Christian  sense. 

3.  The  oath  of  the  Christian  is  also  a  confession  of  faith 
in  the  Triune  God  as  the  omniscient  judge,  but  its  aim  is  a 
social  one — that  of  making  a  statement  worthy  of  credit. 
But  inasmuch  as  an  oath  is  permissible  for  this  end  alone, 
and  not  as  a  matter  of  individual  choice,  it  beloncrs  to  the 
doctrine  of  Christian  truthfalness. 


CHAPTER    SECOND. 

THE  NEW  PERSONALITY,  CREATED  IN  THE  IMAGE  OF  GOD, 
IN  RELATION  TO  ITSELF. 

§    56. 

Christian  Self-love  ;  the  necessary  Grounds  on  vjhich  it  rests. 

True,  i.e.  Christian,  self-love  does  not,  like  natural  self-love, 
exist  of  itself,  but  arises  from  love  to  God,  through 
renunciation  of  self,  or  hatred  of  self,  as  it  is  also  called. 
The  new  personality,  being  formed  after  the  Divine 
image,  is  an  ethical  good  of  absolute  worth ;  nay,  it  is 
a  microcosmic  system  of  goods,  which  must  be  prized, 
protected,  and  promoted  on  all  their  sides,  but  in  the 
order  determined  by  love  as  manifested  in  the  absolute 
sphere.'^ 

J^ote. — The  system  of  goods  involved  in  the  new  personality 
is  divided  in  accordance  with   the  idea  of  God '  (§  6).     This 

'  Christianity  must  be  treated  as  favour,  grace,  election,  and  not  as  law  and 
the  performance  of  works. 

"  [Of  course,  when  the  author  speaks  of  self-love,  he  conceives  of  it  in  all  its 
manifestations  only  in  its  union  with  faith  and  wisdom,  or  hope,  and  therefore 
as  an  activity  of  the  whole  Christian  personality. — Ed.] 

'■>  [Of.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  i.  §  21-27.— Ed.] 


446      §  5G.  THE  NEW  PERSONALITY  IN  RELATION  TO  ITSELF. 

results  from  the  personality  being  made  in  the  image  of  God ; 
it  is  determined  by  the  categories  of  Life  and  Poiver,  of  Moral 
Beauty  and  Harmony,  of  Wisdom  and  Will.  Further,  its 
activity  is  also  determined  by  the  fact  that  its  honour,  "  8o|a," 
is  also  to  be  manifested. 

1.  Our  race  is  highly  esteemed  by  God  (Gen.  i.  26).  The 
wisdom  of  God  delighted  in  the  children  of  men  and 
rejoiced  in  them  (Prov.  viii.).  It  is  an  honour  to  be  a  man. 
Humanity  confers  nobility  (Jas,  iii.  9;  Acts  xvii.  28;  Matt. 
vi.  26-30).  But  this  does  not  arise  from,  man's  empirical 
nature  without  regard  to  its  deficiency  and  corruption,  but 
from  the  fact  that  he  is  destined  to  be  perfect  even  as  our 
Father  in  heaven  is  perfect  (Matt.  v.  48) ;  and  this  remains 
his  destination  even  in  spite  of  sin,  and  attains  realization 
through  the  gospel.  We  belong,  indeed,  like  other  natural 
beings,  to  a  particular  species.  But  whereas,  in  the  case  of 
the  latter,  the  notion  of  a  species  is  formed  by  taking  together 
those  characteristics  which  are  common  to  all  the  individuals 
of  the  species,  and  excluding  those  which  are  not  found  in  all, 
as  being  accidental  with  reference  to  the  notion, — in  the  case 
of  man,  this  logical  method  of  forming  a  notion  from  mere 
empirical  considerations  is  insufficient.  In  order  to  form  a 
true  concept  of  man,  logic  must  become  teleology,  must  there- 
fore become  ethical.  For  since  there  are  also  degenerate 
individuals  belonging  to  our  race,  the  Aristotelian  application 
of  logic  would  result  in  an  idea  of  mankind  which  would 
leave  out  precisely  what  is  best,  what  is  most  human  in  man, 
because  it  does  not  exist  empirically  in  all.  Nay,  since  there 
is  sin  in  all  men,  were  we  to  adopt  this  empirical  method  of 
forming  the  concept  of  man,  we  should  have  to  make  sinful- 
ness an  essential  characteristic  in  it.  What  the  elements  are 
which  belong  to  the  idea  of  man  in  his  true  dignity,  which 
alone  are  capable  of  making  mankind  a  unity,  and  therefore 
also  of  forming  a  true  and  not  merely  a  negative  universal — 
this  does  not  depend  upon  whether  these  elements  are  charac- 
teristic of  the  whole  range  of  human  individuals.  And  so 
Christianity,  in  opposition  to  that  ancient  logical  method,  has 
the  boldness  to  form  its  concept  of  mankind  and  of  true 
humanity  from  the  standard  presented  by  one  individual, 
viz.    Christ.     In  doing  so  it  appeals  against  empiricism,    to 


THE  CHRISTIAN  CONCEPT  OF  HUMANITY.  447 

which  it  bids  defiance,  to  the  sense  of  duty,  to  the  moral 
imperative  which  is  in  all  men ;  and  forms  its  concept  of  man 
in  accordance  with  this  distinctive  property  of  man,  a  property 
wdiich  belongs  also  to  Christ.  It  constructs  the  notion  of 
mankind,  on  the  one  hand,  from  the  archetype  of  Divine- 
human  moral  power  which  has  appeared  in  Christ,  and,  on  the 
other,  from  man's  susceptibility,  his  capacity  to  receive  Christ's 
power.  Thus  Christ  is  humanity  personified ;  for  He  is  true 
humanity,  endowed  with  divine  power ;  He  is  the  honour  of 
our  race  (Eom.  viii.  17).  Moreover,  as  He  Himself  numbers 
Himself  with  mankind,  to  be  a  blessing  and  a  sacred  possession 
to  them,  and  gives  Himself  for  them  in  His  love,  so  God,  too, 
numbers  Him  with  men,  and  believers  with  Him,  so  that  His 
86^a  is  transmitted  to  them,  and  the  Son  becomes  the  first- 
born among  many  hretlircn  through  the  Holy  Spirit  (Eom. 
viii.  29  ;  2  Cor.  v.  14-17  ;  Col.  iii.  9  ;  Eph.  iv.  24).  Look- 
ing upon  Him  as  a  common  possession  of  mankind,  God,  on 
account  of  His  connection  with  humanity,  bears  patiently  with 
those  who  do  not  as  yet  believe,  but  may  become  believers. 
Those  who  are  united  to  Christ  by  personal  faith  are  personally 
objects  of  His  love  (1  John  iii.  1),  and  this  fact  is  the 
foundation  and  justification  of  our  love  to  ourselves,  or  of 
Christian  self-love.  The  latter  rests,  therefore,  as  being  Chris- 
tian, upon  prevenient  Divine  love,  upon  the  fact  that  we  are 
loved  (1  John  iv.  10).  We,  as  simply  empirical  beings,  must 
not  be  the  objects  of  this  self-love,  except  in  so  far  as  we  are 
capable  of  being  redeemed.  Besides,  where  fellowship  with 
God  in  Christ  does  not  exist,  the  suhject  of  Christian  self-love 
is  non-existent ;  whence  it  follows  that  it  is  only  in  Christians 
that  true  self-love  is  to  be  found.  Apart  from  Christ,  on  the 
contrary,  self-love  has  a  false  goal,  and  is  a  non-moral  dis- 
position ;  it  is  rather  a  degenerate  self-love,  a  self-love  run 
wild,  inasmuch  as  it  is  not  directed  to  the  ideal  of  one's  own 
personality  as  found  in  Christ.  We  love  ourselves,  we  love 
our  true  self,  by  denying  our  empirical  self,  by  conceiving 
and  holding  fast  the  true  image  of  ourselves  as  it  lives  in  God 
and  is  hid  in  Christ. 

2.  As  it  is  a  matter  of  experience  that  self-love  is  very 
often  selfishness  or  egoism,  many  have  held  that  it  ought  to  be 
banished  from  ethics  altogether.      But  wrongly  so.      God,  at 


448       §  o«.  THE  NEW  PERSONALITY  IN  RELATION  TO  ITSELF. 

all  events,  is  an  object  of  love  to  Himself,  and  men  are  to  be 
likenesses  of  Him.  It  may,  indeed,  be  said  quite  truly  that 
all  the  subjects  included  in  this  Division  may  be  treated  as 
coming  under  the  duty  of  love  to  God ;  and  we  have,  in  fact, 
referred  to  this  source  all  our  religious  duties  to  ourselves.  It 
is  true  that  Christian  self-love  arises  out  of  love  to  God.  But 
whenever  we  give  ourselves  unconditionally  to  God,  He 
makes  us  objects  of  His  complacency,  ultimate  ends  to  Him- 
self, wills  that  He  should  dwell  as  a  gracious  Father  in  souls 
made  like  unto  Himself,  and  that  we  should  regard  ourselves 
as  He  regards  us.  And  from  this  it  follows  that  our  love 
would  not  love  what  He  loves,  would  not  will  what  He  wills, 
if  we  did  not  also  become  objeets  of  our  own  love.  In 
opposition,  therefore,  to  di  false  mysticism,  which  would  remain 
in  mere  passivity,  in  opposition  to  a  false  repose  in  justifying 
faith  or  in  the  assurance  of  election,  it  is  a  definite  article 
of  doctrine,  a  cardinal  point,  that  the  moral  necessity — not 
20crmissihility — of  Christian  self-love  should  be  acknowledged. 
When  Christ  commands  us  to  love  our  neighbour  as  ourselves 
(Matt,  xxii.  39),  He  thereby  presupposes  self-love,  and  in 
nowise  blames  it.  Without  self-love,  the  "  rrjpecv  eavrov " 
of  1  John  V.  18  would  not  be  possible;  nay,  we  could  not 
even  be  thankful  for  the  Divine  gifts  vouchsafed  us.  But,  to 
be  sure,  one  might  think — no  one  needs  encouraging  to  self- 
love  ;  it  exists  of  itself.  By  no  means !  Selfishness  exists  of 
itself,  whereas  Christian  sclf-lovc  does  not  exist  of  itself  and 
apart  from  self-denial,  any  more  than  any  other  virtue.  Its 
irrcrequisite  and  inward  regulator  is  love  to  God.  For  we  are 
to  love  ourselves  because  God  loves  us.  And  further,  we  are 
to  love  ourselves  as  God  loves  us  and  as  He  would  have  us  be. 
Again,  Christian  self-love  is  the  prerequisite  and  standard  of 
Christian  love  of  one's  neighbour.  For,  on  the  one  hand,  there 
cannot  be  such  a  thing  as  love  to  one's  neighbour  unless 
there  is  a  moral  personality  to  exhibit  it,  and  in  that 
personality,  as  such,  there  must  be  self-love;  while,  on  the 
other  hand,  the  nature  of  self-love  is  determined,  above  all 
things,  by  the  fact  that  we  must  first  of  all  know  how  we 
have  to  love  ourselves,  since  we  are  to  love  our  neighbour  as 
ourselves.  Thus  love  to  God  descends  to  and  assumes  the  form 
of  that  self-love  which  is  godlike,  the  amor  amoris ;  love  to 


§  o7.  CHEISTIAN  SELF-LOVE.  449 

the  personality  as  loving,  and  not  in  any  other  way.  But  if 
true  personal  self-love  means  love  to  the  loving  personality,  we 
see  that  in  putting  others  upon  the  same  footing  as  ourselves, 
it  is  necessary  that  we  love  them  as  manifesting  love  [to 
others].  And  therewith  love  acquires  its  ethical  character 
and  contents ;  the  necessity  for  self-love  passing  over  into 
social  love  is  so  strong,  that  the  individual  loves  himself  truly, 
only  when  he  loves  himself  as  loving,  as  embracing  his  fellow- 
man  in  his  love ;  and  this  in  such  wise  that  he  is  at  first  a 
mere  recipient  of  love,  and  then  also  one  who  spontaneously 
loves.  Thus  Christian  love  takes  shape  as  unselfish  love  to 
our  neighbour,  especially  to  Ids  unselfish  love ;  the  deceitful 
bond  of  apparent,  i.e.  of  selfish  love  is  destroyed,  and  an 
indissoluble,  sacred  interchange  or  chain  of  love  is  formed, 
such  as  Zinzendorf  especially  has  so  often  sung  of  in  his 
hymns. 

In  what  follows  we  have  now  to  treat  of  the  separate 
points  indicated  in  our  thesis.  We  consider,  in  the  first 
place.  Christian  self-love  in  general,  and  then  Christian  self-love 
in  its  s]3ecial  characteristics. 

§57. 

A. — Christian  Self-love ;  its  Nature  in  general. 

Self-love  in  the  Christian  is  the  principle  of  progressive  self- 
culture,  filling  him,  on  the  one  hand,  with  humble  and 
grateful  joy  in  the  work  of  God  which  is  begun  in  him, 
and,  on  the  other,  turning  him  in  Christian  hope  and 
with  living  earnestness  to  the  goal  that  is  set  before 
him.  In  particular,  however,  it  manifests  itself  as 
follows.  (1)  In  relation  to  itself,  it  reveals  itself  («) 
negatively,  in  constant  self-purification,  denial  of  the 
natural  man,  and  protection  of  the  whole  system  of 
goods  which  belong  to  the  personality  ;  in  other  words,  in 
active  self-respect  in  opposition  to  everything  that  would 
dishonour  the  personality.  This  is  Christian  self-love 
under  the  aspect  of  righteousness.  Further,  it  reveals 
itself  (h) positively,  in  Christian  culture  in  the  widest  sense 
2  F 


450  §  57.  CHKISTIAN  SELF-LOVE. 

of  the  word ;  or  iu  other  words,  by  infusing  an  ethical 
spirit  into  (making  ethical)  the  physical  and  mental 
energies,  enjoyment  and  work,  even  on  their  individual 
side.  This  is  positive  Christian  self-love.  (2)  With  regard 
to  others.  Christian  self-love  asserts  itself  iu  the  form  of 
Christian  dignity  of  character ;  negatively,  in  Christian 
independence  and  self-reliance ;  positively,  in  Christian 
care  for  one's  good  name,  and  legitimate  'personal  influence. 
The  realization  and  combination  of  these  different 
elements  is  effected  by  a  truthful  self-manifestation  on 
the  part  of  the  Christian,  and  by  his  choice  and  exercise 
of  a  vocation. 

1.  From  the  fundamental  Christian  virtue,  in  which /a^^5A, 
love,  and  hojvi  etre  united  (§  43,  2),  Christian  self-love  issues 
spontaneously.  For  the  new  personality  is  self-conscious,  not 
unconscious ;  it  cannot  therefore  exist  without  the  Christian 
being  joyfully  aware  of  the  work  of  God  which  is  begun  in 
him  (Phil,  i.),  and  this  knowledge  fills  him  with  thankfulness 
and  humility,  and  also  with  courage.  Looked  at  more  closely, 
tlierefore,  Christian  self-love  means  that  we  value  highly  and 
keep  pure  and  holy  the  divine  work  in  us,  a  work  which  is 
tlie  forming  of  a,  neio  j^crson,  the  realization  to  us  of  a  part  of 
the  highest  good.  And  for  this  very  reason,  Christian  self- 
love  is  infinitely  far  removed  from  that  spiritually  impure, 
Narcissus-like,  self-admiration,  in  which  the  Ego  falls  in  love 
with  its  own  image.  Such  conduct  is  only  possible  where 
there  is  a  lack  of  humble  acknowledgment  of  God's  grace  and 
of  the  effects  of  sin  in  defacing  our  image ;  and  further,  where 
God's  work  in  us  is  regarded  as  something  complete,  a  dead 
product  as  it  were,  whereas  it  is  an  ethical  product,  that  has 
to  be  constantly  reproduced.  In  this  w^ork,  the  new  per- 
sonality which  has  to  be  reproduced  is  itself  actively  engaged, 
its  energies  are  directed  to  itself,  and  it  points  to  a  future  in 
which  all  its  powers  will  become  normal  and  appropriated  by 
the  Christian  principle,  so  that  all  discords  among  them  will 
cease.  It  is  therefore  impossible  for  the  new  Ego  to  remain 
at  a  standstill  in  self-satisfaction.  And  it  is  this  Ego,  not  the 
empirical  one,  which  is  the  object  of  Christian  self-love.     This 


IN  RELATION  TO  OTHERS.  451 

Ego  is,  indeed,  not  a  Platonic  Idea  but  a  reality ;  it  exists, 
however,  only  in  communion  with  Christ,  and  is  at  first  a 
reality  in  principle  merely,  or,  as  it  were,  in  emhryo.  But 
there  is  in  it  the  impulse  to  develop  into  the  pure  and  perfect 
form  of  personality,  of  which  the  archetype  has  been  given 
us  in  Christ  (Col.  iii.  9).  This  growing  manifestation  and 
unfolding  of  the  principle  of  Christian  virtue,  not  merely  in 
momentary  acts  but  as  a  habitually  animating  force,  is  the 
process  in  which  the  personality  branches  out,  as  it  were,  into 
the  Christian  virtues.  But  the  personality  can  only  succeed 
in  bringing  its  whole  inward  domain  into  subjection  to  the 
principle  of  Christian  virtue,  by  carrying  on  a  purifying  course 
of  discipline  with  regard  to  itself,  i.e.  with  regard  to  the 
empirical  personality,  or  through  the  old  man  within  us  dying 
more  and  more.  In  this  way,  the  claims  of  justice  are  satisfied 
with  reference  both  to  the  old  and  the  new  man.  This  is, 
therefore,  the  negative  aspect  of  Christian  virtue  towards  itself,  the 
aspect  of  righteousness,  the  self -respect  of  the  new  man,  in  which 
he  protects  his  purity  and  honour,  and  at  the  same  time  executes 
justice  upon  the  old  man.  The  latter  point  does  not  mean 
that  the  natural  energies  are  to  be  weakened,  for  this  would 
rob  the  new  man  of  some  of  the  organs  of  his  activity,  but 
that  we  are  to  contend  against  the  evil  which  exists  together 
with  the  new,  God-given  nature. 

2.  In  relation  to  others,  Christian  self-assertion  may  legiti- 
mately take  the  form  of  separating  ourselves  from  our 
neighbour  so  far  as  his  sin,  but  not  so  far  as  his  person  is 
concerned.  This  negative  aspect  of  Christian  self-love,  mani- 
fested in  self-assertion  with  reference  to  our  empirical  Ego 
and  to  other  men,  must  then  be  supplemented  by  a  positive 
activity,  the  object  of  which  is  the  improvement  or  culture  of 
that  personality  given  us  by  God,  the  promotion  of  its  life  and 
growth,  in  order  that  we  may  be  able  to  be  of  some  service  to 
the  whole  community,  more  especially  in  our  particular  voca- 
tion. 


452  §  58.  CARE  FOR  PERSONAL  HONOUR. 


B, — Christian  Self-love  ;  its  Special  Characteristics  both  in 
Itself  and  vjith  regard  to  Others. 

I.    CARE  FOR  PERSONAL  HONOUR  IN  ITSELF. 

§  58. 

Care  for  the  honour  of  the  personality  in  itself  comprehends 
the  acquiring  and  perfecting  of  the  goods  which  belong 
to  the  personality,  both  of  a  temporal  and  spiritual 
kind.      It  therefore  includes — 

1 .  With  reference  to  the  tcmjjorcd  life  of  the  senses : 

(a)  Care  for  our  Physical  Existence,  Health  and  Strength, 
and  for  the  maintenance  of  the  right  relation 
between  Work  and  Eecreation ;  in  other  words, 
care  for  virtuous  Well-being ; 

ilj)   for  virtuous  Beauty  and  Purity ; 

(c)  for  virtuous  Ownership  (Property). 

2.  With  reference  to  the  mental  life : 

On  the  intclleetucd  side,  care  for  virtuous  Refinement; 
on  the  side  of  the  loill,  care  for  virtuous  Self-control  and 
Stability  of  Character. 

§  59. 

la.   Care  for  our  Physical  Existence. 

1.  Care  of  the  body  and  bodily  hecdth.  Although  life  is  not 
the  highest  of  goods,  yet  it  is  sinful  to  neglect  to  shorten, 
or  to  destroy  it.  There  are  many  passages  in  Scripture 
referring  to  self-destruction.  Job  xiii.  13  f.,  ii.  9  ;  Judg. 
xvi.  (Samson);  1  Sam.  xxxi.  4  (Saul);  2  Sam.  xvii.  23 
(Ahithophel) ;  Matt,  xxvii.  5  (Judas  Iscariot) ;  Acts  xvi.  27. 
No  express  prohibition  is  given  against  it  (except  in  so  far  as 
it   is  forbidden  in   the   Fifth  (6th)    commandment) ;   but  its 


§  59.  CAr.E  FOR  OUR  PHYSICAL  EXISTENCE.  453 

sinfulness  follows  from  the  universal  proposition,  that  as 
Christians  we  and  all  our  powers  belong  no  longer  to  ourselves 
and  our  own  wills,  but  have  been  bought  by  Christ,  and  are 
dependent  upon  the  Divine  Spirit.  Eom.  xiv.  7  ff. ;  2  Cor. 
V.  15;  1  Cor.  vi.  19;  Phil.  i.  21  f.  The  act  of  suicide 
does  not  consist  in  our  purposely  bringing  death  upon 
ourselves.  E.g.  in  war  on  behalf  of  our  native  land,  or 
to  save  another's  life,  we  may,  in  order  to  fulfil  our  duty, 
have  to  venture  upon  an  undertaking  which  must  end  in 
death.  In  like  manner,  the  Christian  martyrs,  who  pressed 
forward  to  death  in  order  to  evince  their  love  to  Christ,  must 
not  be  called  suicides.  But  in  suicide,  in  addition  to  the 
outward  act  of  destroying  life  or  of  its  arbitrary  renunciation, 
there  is  also  this,  that  the  subject  has  himself  and  his  own 
advantage  in  view,  and  wishes  to  escape  from  certain  evils, 
that  there  is  no  self-sacrifice  for  an  ideal  or  for  a  social  good. 
Its  guilt  therefore  consists  in  the  fact  that  life  is  thrown 
away  wilfully,  whether  from  fear  of  physical  or  moral  evils,, 
or  in  hope  of  a  higher  gain,  as  is  the  case  in  the  suicide  of 
fanaticism.  The  awful  thing  about  this  crime  is,  that  in  the 
wicked  self-will  which  it  displays,  there  is  a  renunciation  of 
obedience,  a  denial  of  dependence  upon  the  Creator,  a  rebellious 
interference  with  His  will  as  Creator  and  Preserver,  allied 
with  unbelief  in  the  avenging  God,  except  where  the  act 
proceeds  from  fanaticism  or  superstition.  The  suicide  does 
not  merely  sin  against  one  side  of  his  nature,  but  so  far  as  he 
can,  he  destroys  the  very  possibility  of  all  moral  activity.  The 
impiety  of  suicide  appears  most  clearly  when  it  arises  from 
worldly  motives.  If  one  has  lost  his  wealth  or  his  reputatioa 
among  men,  it  looks  as  if  it  might  be  from  a  feeling  of  honour 
that  he  commits  suicide.  But  it  is  rather  from  cowardice,, 
which  makes  him  wish  to  escape  from  pain  and  evil  instead  of 
bearing  them  manfully,  preserving  his  inward  honour,  and 
winning  for  himself  by  moral  effort  a  new  stage  of  his  activity, 
and  of  outward  respect  as  well.  Fear  of  moral  temptation  also 
is  no  justification  for  the  evil  deed.  Finally,  the  incurring  of 
disgrace,  violation  in  the  case  of  virgins,  or  the  fear  of  it,  are 
just  as  far  from  making  suicide  permissible.  For  that  which 
is  endured  helplessly  is  dishonouring  neither  in  the  eyes  of 
intelligent  men  nor  in  the   sight  of  God.      Moral  temptation. 


454  §  59.  DUELLING. 

moreover,  when  we  have  not  wantonly  rushed  into  it,  is  not 
to  be  avoided  by  death,  but  to  be  overcome. 

It  is  self-evident  that  self-mutilation  also,  which  the  law 
indeed  forbids,  as  well  as  every  approach  to  suicide  through 
brutal  debauchery,  is  included  in  what  has  been  said,  since  they 
too  employ  the  great  gift  of  life  as  a  means  for  the  ends  of 
egoism.  E.g.,  cutting  of  the  flesh  on  occasions  of  mourning. 
Lev.  xix.  28,  xxi.  5  ;  Deut.  xiv.  1  ;  Jer.  xvi.  6,  xli.  5,  xlvii.  5, 
xlviii.  37;  cf.  1  Cor.  vi.  19;  Phil.  iii.  21. 

§  59ff.  Duelling. 

Single  combat  is  the  settlement  of  a  private  matter  of  honour 
by  engaging  in  personal,  mortal  conflict  with  the 
offender.  It  is  undertaken  in  order  to  compel  the 
offender  to  risk  his  life  in  return  for  the  damage  done  to 
our  honour ;  and  especially  to  show  on  the  part  of  the 
injured  person  that  he  values  his  honour  more  than  he 
does  bis  life,  and  thus  to  re-establish  it.  But  however 
differently  duelling  has  to  be  judged  at  different  times, 
it  must  be  repudiated  as  immoral,  when  regular  legal 
proceedings  can  be  taken. 

The  Literature. — Reinhard,  Moral,  i.  481  f.  linger,  Der 
gerichtliche  ZweikamjJ  hei  den  germanischen  Volkern.  In  the 
Gottingcr  Studien,  1847.  [Schleiermacher,  Christliche  Sittc, 
pp.  625  f.  Zur  Philosophie,  vol.  i.  pp.  614  f.  Rothe,  iii.  pp. 
326  f.  De  Wette,  Christliche  Sittenlehre,  iii.  288  f.  Martensen, 
ii.  i.  p.  425.] 

1.  It  is  evident  that  we  must  pass  a  different  verdict  from 
the  above  upon  judicial  combats,  ordeals,  appeals  to  the  judg- 
ment of  God,  etc.,  among  ancient  nations,  where  single  combat 
was  also  a  public  affair  in  which  whole  nations  were  represented 
(Horatii  and  Curiatii).  But  in  a  settled  state  of  society 
duelling  is  a  relapse  into  the  state  of  nature,  for  here  other 
means  are  available  and  ought  to  be  tried. 

2.  Duelling  is  to  be  condemned — 

(a)  Because  in  it  the  guiltij  and  the  innocent  are  un- 
justly  placed   upon   an  equal  footing.       It   is   true   that  in 


.    §  51).  DUELLING.  455 

a  judicial  trial  they  are  also  placed  on  an  equal  footing 
before  a  decision  is  arrived  at,  but  in  the  latter  case  it  is  right 
that  decides,  while  in  a  duel  it  is  bodily  strength  and 
dexterity.  He  who  has  been  wronged  has  in  the  first  place 
to  risk  his  life,  while  it  may  be  that  the  offender  risks  nothing. 
If  I  am  the  guilty  party,  I  have  no  right,  in  addition  to  this, 
to  threaten  a  good  possessed  by  the  innocent,  viz.  his  life. 
If  I  am  innocent,  I  ought  not  to  have  to  seek  satisfaction  by 
risking  my  life,  which  is  a  good  of  mine.  That  would  be 
prodigal  magnanimity.  Consequently,  two  persons  cannot 
engage  in  a  duel  without  sin.  And  if  it  is  a  matter  of 
dispute  which  is  guilty,  no  decision  can  be  arrived  at  by 
means  of  a  duel. 

(h)  Further,  should  a  duel  take  place,  it  is  morally  futile, 
inasmuch  as  its  end  is  not  really  attained,  for  to  risk  one's 
life  cannot  possibly  be  a  proof  that  one  is  an  honourable 
man,  since  there  is  a  contempt  of  life  that  is  immoral.^ 
ISTatural  courage  may  exist  together  with  the  meanest  disposi- 
tion. Besides,  he  whose  cause  is  not  superior  in  point  of 
justice  may  be  superior  in  point  of  skill.  In  a  duel,  there- 
fore, we  have  recourse  to  the  right  of  the  stronger,  and  this  is 
no  right  at  all.  When  public  opijiion  assumes  that  a  man's 
honour  is  re-established  because  he  has  fought  a  duel,  it 
deceives  itself,  it  is  too  lax.      Other  proofs  are  required. 

(c)  Duelling  being  thus  immoral,  we  can  only  defend  our 
outward  honour  by  means  of  it,  at  the  expense  of  inward 
lionour.  Since  the  duel  is  inadequate  to  accomplish  its 
end,  a  true  inward  sense  of  honour  must  show  itself,  wherever 
false  notions  of  honour  have  crept  into  a  comnnmity,  by 
bravely  checking  these,  and  thus  awaking  a  common  spirit  of 
rectitude,  which,  when  it  is  vigorous,  will  find  out  suitable 
means  for  the  protection  of  outward  reputation.  And  here 
organized  means  of  protecting  outward  honour  must  certainly  be 
taken  into  consideration.  Courts  of  honour,  when  properly 
instituted,    will  be  a  more  effective  safeguard  of  our  rights 

^  Ko  one  can  engage  in  a  dnel  without  taking  into  account  the  danger  to  which 
he  exposes  his  own  life  and  the  life  of  others,  and  thus  implicitly  giving  his 
consent  to  the  worst  results  that  may  ensue,  and  being  responsible  for  them. 
American  duels  are  consequently  not  so  very  different  in  principle  from  others 
as  is  supposed. 


456  §  60.  CONTINUATION. 

than  duelling.  And  all  suspicion  of  cowardice  is  obviated 
in  the  case  of  one  who  refuses  to  engage  in  a  duel,  when  he 
shows  in  his  whole  life  that  he  is  honourable,  manly,  and 
Christian. 

Note. — Among  military  men,  where  bravery  and  manly  spirit 
are  professional  virtues,  the  stain  of  cowardice  is  an  absolute 
disqualification.  Here  the  mere  conventional  rule  that,  in  certain 
cases,  injuries  must  be  expiated  by  means  of  a  duel  can  of  course 
have  no  authority.  But  when  in  their  case  the  state  itself  appoints 
courts  of  honour,  with  the  j)ower  to  determine  that  a  duel  should 
take  place,  and  thus  in  a  certain  measure  lends  it  its  sanction, 
still  more  when  it  makes  one  who  avoids  such  a  duel  sulTer  for 
so  doing,  then  a  duel  becomes  injudicial  combat.  But  although 
an  individual  may  thus  engage  in  a  duel  without  sin,  the 
guilt  of  it,  while  taken  off  his  shoulders,  falls  upon  the  legal 
ordinance.  In  other  instances,  on  the  contrary,  duelling  inflicts 
an  injury  upon  the  state,  especially  where  it  is  defended  as  a 
custom  that  is  moral  in  the  case  of  the  nobility.  The  state,  it 
is  then  said,  cannot  attach  that  value  to  honour  which  class 
notions  demand.  But  it  is  a  usurpation  of  the  power  that  Ijelongs 
to  constituted  authority,  for  any  one  thus  to  take  the  law  into 
his  own  hands.  In  well-ordered  states,  no  one  has  the  right — 
apart  from  self-defence — to  seek  self-redress,  and  employ  force 
in  protecting  a  good  which  the  state  as  such  does  not  recognise. 
In  early  times  all  freemen,  and  not  merely  the  nobility,  had  the 
right  to  prosecute  private  feuds.  There  is  thus  all  the  less 
reason  why  the  nobility  should  claim  a  position  of  moral 
exemption  in  this  matter.  When,  in  consequence  of  false 
prejudices  on  the  part  of  the  nobility  with  regard  to  their  class 
honour,  the  practice  of  duelling  is  made  persistent  and  contagious, 
it  becomes  the  other  classes  of  society  to  maintain  their  inde- 
pendence, not  by  imitating  the  example  that  is  given  them,  but 
by  offering  a  gallant  resistance  to  it  from  the  standpoint  of 
Christian  culture. 


§  60.   Continuation. 
Care  of  the  Body. 

1.  On  its  positive  side,  careful  attention  to  life,  health,  and 
strength  is  incumbent  upon  us  as  a  duty,  since  the  body — not 
merely  the  gross  matter  of  it,  but  also  that  spiritual  quality  in 
it,  that  plastic  power,  namely,  which  remains  the  same  amid 


CARE  OF  THE  BOD 7.  457 

the  change  of  bodily  elements  and  nutritive  substances,  but 
which  may  be  impaired  as  well  as  strengthened — since  the 
body  is  not  merely  accidental  to  man,  but  is  that  side  of  him- 
self which  gives  him  actual  existence  in  the  world.  In  order 
to  recommend  the  old  "  mens  sana  in  corpore  sano,"  we  do  not 
need  to  show  in  detail  how  important  for  the  mind  of  man  are 
the  health  and  strength  of  that  organ  by  means  of  which  alone 
he  can  directly  influence  the  world,  and  how  intimately  even 
mental  powers,  especially  imagination  and  memory,  are  con- 
nected witli  the  constitution  of  the  body.  Care  of  the  body  is 
therefore  a  moral  duty  (Col.  ii.  23, /ir?  ev  dcpetBia  crcofiaTO<i),  and 
in  performing  this  duty  we  must  not  only  see  that  the  powers 
of  the  body  are  not  wasted,  that  the  necessaries  of  life  are  not 
denied  it,  that  our  vital  energy  itself  is  not  weakened  by 
austerities  in  the  way  of  exertion  and  needless  abstinence,  but 
we  must  also  endeavour  to  make  the  body  capable  of  exertion. 
It  is  essential  to  the  freedom  of  man  that  he  should  seek  to 
render  himself  independent  of  terrestrial  influences,  of  wind 
and  weather,  and  so  train  his  bodily  organ  all  round  as  to 
make  it  ready  to  accept  the  impulses  of  the  spirit  and  carry 
them  energetically  into  execution.  Eom.  vi.  13,  19  (/xeX?;  for 
the  7rvev/j.a).  1  Cor.  vi.  13  (o  Kvpio<i  Ta>  acofiari).  Eom. 
viii.  13  [irpd^ea  a-co/Maro';  Oavarovv).  Training  of  the  body, 
in  the  case  of  the  male  sex  more  particularly,  has  to  be  carried 
out  by  means  of  gymnastics,  drill  and  the  like.  Female 
culture,  on  the  contrary,  nmst  not  be  carried  on  by  gymnastics, 
but  to  early  participation  in  household  duties ;  let  there  be  no 
emancipation  of  women.  With  regard  to  attention  to  health 
in  particular,  each  one  must  adhere  to  a  certain  diet.  It  is  a 
necessary  part  indeed  of  full  self-consciousness  to  distinguish 
between  what  is  beneficial  to  the  body  and  what  is  injurious ; 
but,  unless  sickness  or  the  doctor  prescribes  otherwise,  we 
must  also  beware  of  scrupulosity,  or  at  all  events  be  able  to 
dispense  with  it,  since  it  may  degenerate  into  a  slavish  and 
legal  spirit,  which  becomes  a  burden  both  to  ourselves  and 
others.  Finally,  as  regards  strcnrjth,  what  we  should  attend  to 
is  not  so  much  to  make  ourselves  capable  of  great  mouientary 
achievements,  explosions  as  it  were  of  power,  but  rather 
to  cultivate  endurance  within  the  limits  of  our  individual 
strength ;  endurance  imparts  more  of  an  ethical  character  to 


458  §  Cl.  CONTINUATION. 

our  strength,  and  we  derive  more  real  advantage  from  it  than 
from  exercising  ourselves  with  a  view  to  great,  athletic, 
momentary  achievements.      Bodily  endurance  is  the  earthly 

support  of  VTTO/XOVi]. 

2.  Attention  to  the  body  and  to  bodily  health  is,  however, 
something  pitiful  and  unworthy,  when — as  happens  in  various 
ways,  and  especially  in  the  bathing  season — it  becomes  a 
worship  of  health,  in  which  the  moral  act  is  almost  entirely 
swallowed  up  in  the  pursuit  of  one  object — viz.  to  vegetate. 
It  is  a  disgrace  for  a  sensible  man,  not  to  speak  of  a  Christian, 
to  make  this  the  end  and  centre  of  his  life-functions,  the 
point  upon  which  he  concentrates  all  his  active  energies. 
Plato  refuses  to  provide  a  physician  for  sucli  people  in  his 
Eepublic.  This  seems  harsh,  but  it  may  be  just  as  humane, 
as  wlien  bath-keepers  and  doctors  contend  for  such  men  as 
their  prey — nay,  it  might  help  to  set  them  all  the  sooner  on 
their  feet.  The  body  is  not  an  end  in  itself,  but  a  means. 
We  ought  not  to  regard  even  death  as  the  greatest  of  evils. 
Love  of  life  must  have  its  limits,  as  well  as  fear  of  death 
(Matt.  X.  28,  xvi.  25  ;  John  xii.  25  ;  1  John  iii.  16).  It  is 
irreligious  for  a  mature  mind  to  succumb  to  death  only  with 
reluctance.  Eor  then  the  last  moment  of  life  becomes  a  con- 
fession of  bondage,  of  a  separation  of  our  will  from  the  will  of 
God.  To  the  Christian,  on  the  contrary,  death  does  not  come 
as  a  surprise,  because  he  has  learned  to  carry  "  memento 
mori "  into  the  midst  of  life,  and  can  thus  turn  even  death 
into  something  that  he  does,  not  merely  that  he  suffers,  and 
make  it  a  work  of  willing  and  joyful  surrender.  He  goes 
from  this  eartlily  scene,  he  is  not  dragged  from  it  like  a 
prisoner. 

§  61.   Continuation. 

Christian  Care  for  Virtuous  Happiness. 

Christian  self-love  consists  further  (§  58a)  in  care  for 
virtuous  happiness,  to  which  belongs  especially  the 
moral  relation  between  work  and  enjoyment,  including 
recreation. 

1.  It    is    a    matter    of   dispute    whether    enjoyment    and 


CHRISTIAN'  CARE  FOR  VIRTUOUS  HAPPINESS.  459 

recreation  may  be  made  objects  of  moral  volition,  or  whether 
they  are  to  be  regarded  not  as  objects  especially  aimed  at,  but 
simply  as  concomitants  of  a  moral' act  directed  to  something 
else.  There  are  moralists  who  look  upon  everything  which 
is  not  directly  an  act  of  will  as  indolence,  and  something 
immoral,  or  at  least  refuse  to  recognise  any  moral  element 
in  enjoyment  and  recreation.  Fichte  holds  that  no  other 
recreation  than  a  change  of  work  is  necessary,  and  it  is  indeed 
true  that  many  do  not  require  anything  more  the  whole  day 
long.  Some  also  appeal  to  the  fact,  that  every  moral  action 
has  an  inward  pleasure  accompanying  it.  But  if  active  work 
is  to  be  carried  on  without  intermission,  then  even  though 
there  be  a  change  from  one  kind  of  work  to  another,  men 
become  mere  working  machines ;  they  lose  the  clearness  of 
self-consciousness,  as  well  as  freedom,  and  the  result  is  that 
work  itself  loses  its  intrinsic  moral  value.  Sleep,  at  all  events, 
remains  as  something  that  must  receive  ethical  construction, 
and  is  a  proof  that  the  ethical  must  not  be  confined  to 
positive  and  active  work  in  opposition  to  enjoyment  and 
recreation.  Death  likewise,  which  cannot  be  regarded  as  an 
act  in  the  productive  sense,  nevertheless  falls  within  the  circle 
of  moral  duty.  On  the  other  side,  that  life  becomes  dull  and 
empty  which  is  wholly  given  up  to  enjoyment.  It  is  pleasure- 
seekers  and  idlers  who,  for  the  most  part,  are  overtaken  with 
a  disgust  of  life.  Xow  that  we  have  indicated  the  two 
extremes,  the  way  is  clear  for  a  solution  of  the  question 
in  hand. 

2.  It  cannot  be  denied  that  all  morality  depends  upon 
every  moment  being  determined  by  the  will,  so  that  an  act  of 
will  may  continue  to  operate  throughout  a  series  of  moments. 
Now,  we  found  at  an  earlier  stage,  that  with  relation  to  God, 
two  forms  of  self-determination  must  be  distinguished,  viz. 
a  receptive  form  (faith)  and  a  spontaneously  active  form  (love). 
Consequently  it  is  morally  right,  and  even  a  duty,  to  afford 
cpportunities  for  hath  of  these  in  our  earthly  life.  But  this  must 
be  done  in  such  a  way  that  everything  may  bear  the  stamp  of 
personality,  while  the  vvevfia  gives  to  everything  its  pervading 
tone.  Whatever  is  natural  in  the  way  of  enjoyment  and 
recreation  must  be  brought  about  by  an  act  of  personal 
volition.      It  is  the  duty  of  every  one,  not  to  renounce  the 


460  §  61.  CONTINUATION. 

corporeal  side  of  his  nature,  but  by  an  act  of  will  to  submit 
to  be  determined  by  it  in  accordance  with  the  laws  of  physical 
life,  and  therefore  to  accept  freely  whatever  tends  to  promote 
life.  But  since  to  the  Christian  physical  life  is  required 
merely  as  an  organ, — not  as  an  end  in  itself — for  he  remains 
a  Christian  even  in  enjoyment, — we  have  here  the  necessary 
limitation  of  what  has  just  been  said.  It  is  immoral  and 
base,  especially  for  the  Christian,  to  surrender  himself  abso- 
lutely to  enjoyment  for  even  a  single  moment :  i.e.  to  suffer 
his  personality  to  be  swallowed  up  in  the  mere  natural  life, 
and  the  mere  spirit  of  nature.  This  holds  good  of  all  sorts  of 
enjoyment,  of  eating  and  drinking,  sexual  love  in  marriage, 
the  excitement  of  social  pleasure,  amusement,  and  the  like. 
And  since  the  moral  element  in  all  enjoyment  and  recreation 
depends  on  their  being  brought  about  by  an  act  of  personal 
volition,  moral  freedom  is  preserved.  And  this  holds  good 
even  with  regard  to  sleep.  The  rule  should  be,  the  day  for 
work,  the  night  for  rest.  Any  subversion  of  this  rule  is 
opposed  to  the  laws  of  physical  life,  and  also  anti-social. 
Among  healthy  men,  sleep  ought  to  be  determined  by  an  act  of 
will,  both  as  regards  its  time  and  its  duration.  Our  moral 
strength  ought  also  to  be  sufhcient  to  determine  the  hour  at 
which  we  shall  awake,  no  less  than  to  enable  us  at  times  to 
dispense  with  our  nightly  rest  altogether ;  it  ought,  finally, 
to  give  us  sleep  at  the  proper  time,  and  bring  our  spirit  into  a 
state  of  peaceful  harmony  before  we  lay  ourselves  down,  so 
that  we  may  not  be  robbed  of  sleep  by  care  or  sense  or  by 
carrying  on  our  work  in  our  dreams.  If  we  have  mental  self- 
control,  our  mind  will  not  continue  to  work  like  a  machine 
against  our  will,  but  will  succeed  in  willing  to  partake  of  such 
recreation  as  may  fill  up  in  a  moral  manner  the  time  devoted 
to  the  strengthening  of  the  bodily  organ.  It  ought  to  be  a 
rule  with  every  one,  never  to  lay  himself  down  to  rest  before 
he  has  brought  his  soul  into  the  peace  of  God.  If  this  rule 
were  followed,  much  of  that  morbid  stuff  would  be  done  away 
with,  which  accumulates  and  is  the  cause  of  confusion  and 
perversity  in  our  sleep  (cf.  Prov,  vi.  6-11,  xx.  13,  xxiv.  33  ; 
Matt.  xxvi.  40  f.  ;  Luke  v.  5  ;  2  Cor.  xi.  27 ;  2  Thess.  iii.  8). 
Now,  when  the  spirit,  by  an  act  of  moral  determination, 
has  given  itself  to  enjoyment  and  opened  itself  to  the  influ- 


ENJOYMENT  AND  RECREATION.  461 

ences  of  nature  for  the  purpose  of  recreation,  it  has  voluntarily 
retired  for  the  time  being  from  active  productivity.  Con- 
sequently, it  is  opposed  to  ethical  principles  to  turn  recreation 
again  into  work,  since  it  is  a  necessary  means  for  restoring 
strength  to  the  bodily  organs,  which  are  also  required  by  the 
spirit  for  its  purely  spiritual  work.  But  all  the  while,  the 
personality  of  the  Christian  is  not  absorbed  in  nature ;  it 
remains  awake  in  its  position  of  authority,  even  in  sleep.  It 
is  a  personality  made  in  the  image  of  God.  Consequently,  it 
wards  off  whatever  is  wrong  and  impure  ;  in  the  midst  of 
recreation  and  enjoyment  conscience  never  ceases  to  act, — 
it  does  not  lie  in  wait  outside  our  enjoyment,  meditating 
and  fretting  about  it,  and  so  destroying  it,  but  is  innnanent  as 
an  ever-observant  eye  and  pure  impulse,  which  suffers  no 
injury  to  be  done  to  it,  and  it  summons  us  to  work  again  at 
the  proper  time,  viz.  when  the  sense  of  physical  life  is  once 
more  aroused  within  us,  and  we  are  conscious  that  our  strength 
is  restored.  And  this  holds  good  both  when  we  are  awake 
and  when  we  are  asleep. 

3.  In  enjoyment  and  recreation,  moreover,  the  true  freedom 
of  the  Christian  is  preserved  by  that  unceasing  and  vital 
communion  which  he  maintains  with  God  in  Christ,  and 
which,  though  differing  at  different  times  both  in  measure  and 
degree,  is  yet  essential  to  his  nature  as  a  new  man.  For  then, 
even  when  he  is  determined  by  nature  (in  a  free,  moral  way), 
he  can  regard  himself  as  determined  by  God,  and  can  be  thus 
determined  through  his  own  volition.  Our  enjoyment  is  con- 
secrated, is  at  once  enlmnced  and  idealised,  when  we  regard 
the  means  through  which  it  comes  as  a  gift  of  God,  and 
render  Him  thanks  for  His  gift.  Thus  it  becomes  clear  how 
even  in  enjoyment  and  recreation  the  Christian  maintains  his 
filial  relationship  to  God.  It  is  a  false  spirituality,  due  to 
pride  and  ingratitude,  that  would  exclude  this  region  of  life 
from  the  sphere  of  Ethics.  The  pleasure,  too,  which  we  de- 
rive from  the  senses  need  not  be  changed  into  or  lost  in 
the  thought  of  God  ;  but  while  the  sense  of  God  ought  to 
be  present  in  our  enjoyment,  we  should  experience  a  real 
pleasure  in  the  gift  itself.  E.g.,  if  in  walking  in  a  garden  we 
come  to  a  beautiful  flower  and  stop  to  admire  it,  it  is  not 
necessary,  in  order  to  make  such  a  moment  a   Christian  and 


462  §  61.  CONTINUATIOX. 

moral  one,  that  tlie  flower  should  give  rise  to  contemplations 
concerning  the  attributes  of  God,  or  that  our  enjoyment  should 
be  transformed  into  formal  prayer.  The  pure  enjoyment  which 
we  feel  is  in  itself  quite  consistent  with  the  spirit  of  prayer, 
Col.  ii.  23  ;  1  Tim.  vi.  3,  iv.  3  K  ;  Eom.  xiv.  2-6,  and  is,  in  its 
own  way,  an  honouring  of  God  and  well-pleasing  to  Him, 

4,  The  sympathy  which  is  always  a  property  of  personality 
is  connected  with  the  fact,  that  we  prefer  to  enjoy  physical 
'pleasures,  such  as  eating  and  drinking,  in  the  society  of  others 
rather  than  by  ourselves.  For  ]iersonal  fellowslivp  includes  the 
individual  self-consciousness  and  stimulates  it,  so  that  the 
mere  enjoyment  we  derive  from  the  senses  is  raised  to  the 
rank  of  a  social  pleasure — always,  however,  on  the  supposition 
that  those  who  meet  together  do  so  harmlessly,  and  can  thus 
really  "  enjoy  "  each  other's  society.  To  this  end  it  is  requisite 
that  those  in  company  should  yield  themselves  to  each  other, 
with  no  other  purpose  than  to  reveal  themselves  as  it  were,  to 
let  themselves  be  seen,  and  without  calculation  or  constraint 
to  bring  to  view  what  is  in  them — of  course  in  a  harmless 
sense.  On  the  one  side  it  is  necessary  that,  instead  of  dis- 
playing vanity  or  sensitive  reserve,  one  should  possess  some 
sense  of  humour  or  irony  with  regard  to  liimself,  and  accord- 
ingly that  he  should  learn  to  surrender  himself  to  good-natured 
humour  on  the  part  of  others,  and  thus  to  look  at  himself  from 
an  objective  point  of  view.  On  the  other  side,  it  is  necessary 
that  we  unsuspiciously  appropriate  whatever  is  said  and  done 
by  others :  over-wise  criticism  is  folly ;  it  destroys  pleasure 
both  in  ourselves  and  others,  and  leads  to  cynicism.  The 
pleasure  of  the  fault-finder  is  folly ;  it  is  a  parasitical  plant 
that  preys  on  the  trunk  of  humanity,  Thersites,  the  critical, 
censorious  character,  would  be  less  common,  if  only  men  made 
it  clear  to  themselves  that  unloving,  heartless  egoism  was  at 
the  bottom  of  it. 

It  follows,  further,  from  the  same  principle  of  personality, 
that  it  is  a  sign  of  moral  imperfection  when  people  know 
no  better  way  of  spending  the  time  of  social  recreation  than  by 
engaging  in  amusements  where  every  one  puts  himself  at  the 
disposal  of  chance — as  in  games  of  hazard — instead  of  finding 
recreation  in  the  free  play  of  minds,  whether  in  serious  or 
sportive  conversation.      Card-playing  is  objectionable  in  so  far 


MEANS  OF  EECREATION.  463 

as  chance  is  made  the  one  power  to  which  all  the  players 
must  passively  submit.  And  since  there  is  little  charm  in 
such  amusement  of  itself,  a  further  means  of  attraction  is  yevy 
apt  to  be  added,  in  the  shape  of  a  money-stake.  Now,  it  is 
true  that  this  might  simply  show  that  we  are  inwardly  inde- 
pendent of  what  we  possess ;  but  we  have  quite  other  oppor- 
tunities of  showing  this ;  in  a  mere  empty  amusement  it  is 
really  the  hope  of  gain  that  is  the  attraction.  Amusement, 
too,  runs  the  risk  here  of  forfeiting  its  proper  character;  for 
it  ceases  to  be  what  it  ought  when  it  becomes  a  work,  a  desire 
for  profit,  or  even  when  it  excites  the  passions  instead  of  restor- 
ing the  balance  of  our  physical  and  mental  powers.  The 
highest  form  of  recreation  is  to  be  found  in  free  conversation, 
which  should  therefore  be  regarded  as  an  art.  It  is  onlj^ 
successful  when  it  is  not  a  work  in  any  sense, — for  it  must 
continue  to  be  a  recreation, — and  is  at  the  same  time  neither 
arbitrary  nor  desultory,  but  when  speech  and  reply  fit  in 
easily  with  each  other.  Further,  the  conversation  must  not 
be  usurped  by  one  individual ;  for  whatever  is  said  should  be 
fruitful,  and  stimulate  some  response  in  those  who  listen.  The 
Apostle  requires  our  speech  to  be  with  grace,  and  to  have  salt 
and  seasoning.      Col.  iv.  6  ;  Mark  ix.  50. 

5.  The  means  to  be  employed  for  the  purpose  of  recreation 
and  enjoyment,  as  well  as  the  method  of  using  them,  are,  on 
the  negative  side,  dependent  upon  the  limitations  arising  from 
the  other  moral  spheres.  These  must  not  be  injured  but 
promoted  by  enjoyment;  for  enjoyment,  while  in  itself  a 
proper  object  of  volition,  is  such,  not  in  the  sense  of  being  a 
final  aim,  but  only  as  a  means.  On  the  positive  side,  the 
means  of  enjoyment  must  be  made  to  depend  upon  the 
principle  which  is  peculiar  to  this  sphere,  viz.  the  ccsthdic 
principle.  Here  the  question  is.  What  will  promote  a  sense 
of  harmonious  personal  life  ?  Too  much  eating  and  drinking, 
as  well  as  epicurism,  must  therefore  be  characterised  as 
morally  reprehensible,  Phil.  iii.  18,  19  :  the  gastronomist  is 
simply  a  man  who  is  all  tongne  or  palate.^  But  by  a 
beautiful  arrangement,  it  is  the  tongue  itself  that  we  use  in 
speaking,  and  in  that  table-talk  which  alone  gives  to  a  meal 

1  With  regard  to  intemperance,  vid.  Gen.  ix.  21  f. ;  Luke  xxi.  34  ;  1  Pet.  iv.  3 ; 
1  Cor.  vi.  10  ;  Rom.  xiii.  13. 


464  §  G2.  VIRTUOUS  PUEITY  AND  BEAUTY. 

its  true  moral  seasoning  and  consecration.  Since  work  is  the 
real  aim  in  enjoyment  and  recreation,  and  since  the  latter  are 
therefore  objects  of  moral  volition  only  for  this  reason,  and  not 
for  their  own  sakes  as  though  they  were  final  aims, — it  might 
seem  as  if  the  best  course  were  to  take  such  things  for  means 
of  enjoyment  as  are  a  work  in  themselves.  The  more  refined 
esthetic  pleasures,  for  instance,  combine  the  two  in  various  ways. 
It  is  indeed  true,  that  virtuous  happiness  must  be  sought  not 
merely  in  enjoyment  as  such,  but  also  in  work  itself.  But  if 
work  itself  be  made  a  means  of  enjoyment,  then  the  latter  is 
the  real  aim,  and  the  former  cannot  be  content  with  such  a 
subordinate  moral  position  :  what  is  morally  requisite  in  work 
is  not  satisfied.  Dilettantism  in  art  or  science  can  only  be 
morally  justified  as  a  higher  kind  of  play  on  the  part  of  our 
powers ;  it  must  not  seek  to  replace  the  true  moral  work 
which  belongs  to  these  spheres — nor,  indeed,  can  it  do  so. 
And  just  as  little  ought  the  spheres  of  the  beautiful  and  of 
science  to  be  put  forward  as  absolute  ends  in  themselves,  at 
the  expense  of  the  other  moral  spheres  [as  if  they  alone 
brought  true  happiness].  Sound  science  points  of  its  own 
accord  to  practice,  and  true  art  does  not  idolize  its  objects  nor 
suffer  itself  to  be  idolized,  but  seeks  to  lend  grace  to  morality. 

§  62. 

11).    Virtuous  Purity  and  Beautij. 

1.  Their  connection.  Purity  and  beauty  are  closely  con- 
nected. The  former  is  the  negative  condition  of  the  latter ; 
hence  simplicity  and  modesty  are  requisite  above  everything 
else  in  the  sphere  of  art,  or  the  world  of  the  morally  beautiful. 
The  beautiful  must  not  indeed,  any  more  than  science,  be 
measured  by  a  standard  external  to  itself;  but  it  is  in  secret, 
inward  alliance  with  morality,  it  is  a  manifestation  of  the 
latter,  although  it  obeys  its  own  law.  And  since  this  law 
demands,  above  all  things,  that  the  world  of  phenomena  or  of 
forms  be  inspired  with  life,  that  matter,  or  at  least  its  forms, 
be  brought  under  the  sway  of  the  ideal,  it  follows  that  the 
beautiful  is  corrupted  by  every  intrusion  of  an  element  of 
sense  that  has  not  been  thus  subdued.     Wherever,  says  Eothe, 


PUEITY.       THE  PASSIONS.  465 

sensuous  brilliancy  of  colouring  is  meant  to  dazzle,  or  sensual 
wantonness  to  allure,  the  beautiful  is  destroyed.  The  same 
thing  happens  also  when  the  material  element  is  so  predomi- 
nant as  to  cause  loss  of  buoyancy,  dulness,  and  insipidity. 

2.  With  regard  now  to  each  of  these  by  itself,  what  has 
been  advanced  (§  61)  concerning  enjoyment  applies  also  to 
furity  ;  but  at  the  same  time  the  latter  must  also  be  brought 
into  relation  to  our  active  powers  in  the  narrower  sense  of 
the  word.  Christian  purity  therefore  demands  not  only  that 
we  preserve  self-control,  self-command,  temperance  in  enjoy- 
ment of  every  kind,  but  also  that  an  inward  measure  or 
restraint  be  exhibited  in  all  that  we  do. 

The  "pasdons  especially  must  here  be  brought  under  con- 
sideration. Many  are  of  opinion  that  these  are  altogether 
reprehensible,  because  they  imply  the  being  affected  by  a 
sensual  stimulus.  And  they  adduce  in  support  of  this  posi- 
tion, James  i.  19,  20  :  "The  wrath  of  man  worketh  not  the 
righteousness  of  God."  This  is  no  doubt  only  too  common  ; 
but  this  is  only  a  reason  for  being  slow  to  wrath  and  main- 
taining self-control  (v.  19).  In  Eph.  iv.  31,  Col.  iii.  8,  it  is 
true  that  that  anger  is  forbidden  which  is  accompanied  witli 
bitterness  and  contempt ;  but  on  the  other  side,  the  New 
Testament  often  speaks  of  o/37>;  on  the  part  of  God,  and 
therefore  of  an  anger  that  is  akin  to  ^7}Xo?,  and  such  f>}Xo9 
accompanied,  too,  by  mental  emotion  is  related  also  of  Jesus. 
It  is  certainly  true  that  Christian  purity  demands  freedom 
from  passion,  for  the  Christian  ought  never  to  act  from  mere 
passion ;  but  it  does  not  follow  from  this  that  our  'pa&sions~ 
are  reprehensible.  As  certainly  as  all  passions  are  unethical, 
in  which  the  spirit  submits  to  the  domination  of  the  senses, 
so  surely  do  such  impulses  contribute  to  the  goodness  of 
human  nature,  since  the  latter  has  been  constituted,  not  only 
with  a  view  to  common,  but  also  to  extraordinary  occasions.. 
When  our  passions  are  enlisted  in  the  service  of  the  good, 
they  increase  our  strength  to  do  what  is  right ;  they  double 
a  man,  as  it  were,  and  are  given  him  not  only  as  a  means  of 
protection  for  his  physical  and  moral  life,  but  also  to  promote 
the  energy  of  his  self-manifestations.  Consequently  they  are 
not  to  be  eradicated.  He  who  cannot  grow  indignant  at  what 
is  evil  has  lost  all  strength  of  will,  the  elasticity  of  his  moral 

2  G 


466         §  62.  VIRTUOUS  PUEITV  AND  BEAUTY. 

life  is  relaxed.  The  one  thing  of  importance  here,  as  in  the 
case  of  enjoyment,  is,  that  no  loss  should  accrue  to  the  Christian 
personality  itself.  It  must  therefore  never  suffer  itself  to  be 
carried  away  by  those  sensual  impulses  which  it  cannot 
approve — such  as  revengefulness,  heartlessness,  envy,  selfish- 
ness, over-self-estimation.  And  even  when  the  personality 
is  the  source  of  the  impulse,  and  the  Christian  allows  his  will 
to  go  along  with  the  emotion  that  takes  powerful  possession 
of  his  spiritual  and  physical  life,  the  personality  must  by  no 
means  lose  itself  either  wholly  or  in  part;  it  must  not  be 
"  carried  out  of  itself,"  by  suffering  the  mere  physical  emotion 
to  escape  from  under  its  own  central  control.  It  must,  on 
the  contrary,  remain  at  the  helm,  like  the  steersman,  who, 
while  he  permits  himself  to  be  swept  forward  on  his  course 
by  wind  and  wave,  still  keeps  full  and  clear  possession  of  his 
senses,  and  retains  his  power  to  guide.  By  this  it  is  not 
meant  that  the  ruling  will  should  merely  stand  calmly  on  the 
watch,  and,  as  it  were,  outside  the  effect  which  is  l3eing 
produced.  In  such  a  case,  the  strength  of  the  passion  would 
be  broken  at  the  outset  by  a  duality.  For  the  whole  person- 
ality would  not  be  given  to  it,  and  yet  the  strength  of  a 
passion  depends  upon  such  a  personal  unity  and  totality. 
But  at  the  same  time,  the  personality  must  continue  to  be 
immanent  in  the  passion ;  if  it  loses  itself  for  even  a  single 
moment,  the  purity  of  the  effect  produced  is  forfeited.  It  is 
evident  from  what  has  l^een  said,  that  for  a  passion  to  be 
moral,  presupposes  the  acquisition  of  some  moral  capital, 
which  operates  of  itself  without  any  special  design  and  con- 
sideration. He  who  has  none  cannot  yield  to  passion  without 
sin,  nor  indeed  can  he  act  at  all  without  sin.  Passions, 
therefore,  bring  to  the  test  the  moral  acquisitions  we  have 
made.  They  do  not  lie,  they  are  honest.  The  ISTew  Testa- 
ment speaks  not  merely  of  %«/?«,  but  also  of  ayaWcdadai, 
^eeiv  TTvev/jiaTi,  efx^pi/ubdadai,  with  opyt],  ^t^Xo?  (Eom,  xii.  1 1  ; 
1  Thess.  V.  19  ;  Matt.  v.  8,  22  ;  Eph.  iv.  26,  31  ;  Mark  iii.  5  ; 
James  i.  19  ;  2  Cor,  vii.  1 ;  1  John  iii.  3).  But  where  there 
is  a  natural  tendency  to  passionate  anger,  it  is  of  special 
importance  that  a  discipline  of  "  katharsis  "  should  be  adopted, 
for  such  a  tendency  deranges  the  harmony  both  of  individual 
and  social  life,  and  is  a  hindrance  to  the  life  of  prayer. 


VIRTUOUS  BEAUTY.  467 

3.  Ill  particular,  is  cJiastity  an  essential  part  of  purity  ? 
Here,  too,  the  fundamental  law  is — the  life  of  sense  is  not 
meant  to  rule  over  the  spirit,  and  this  is  always  what  happens, 
unless  it  is  itself  governed  by  the  spirit.  Every  extra-matri- 
monial gratification  of  the  sexual  impulse  is  sin,  a  desecration 
of  the  temple  of  the  Holy  Spirit — a  degradation.  Vid.  1  Cor. 
vi.  13-20  ;  Gal.  v,  19  ;  Col.  iii.  5  ;  Eom.  i.  24  sq.,  where  various 
other  forms  of  unchastity  are  named.  The  general  expression 
is  iropveia.  But  married  intercourse  is  not  sin,  and  it  is 
immoral  to  regard  it  as  not  belonging  to  the  beneficent  order 
of  nature  (Matt.  xix.  4  f . ;  1  Tim.  iv.  3).  But  in  marriage, 
also,  chastity  must  be  practised  —  i.e.,  decency,  modesty. 
Everything  is  summed  up  in  saying  that  the  body  is,  and  is 
ever  to  continue,  a  temple  of  the  Holy  Spirit ;  that  thus  the 
spirit  may  have  dominion  over  the  body,  not  the  animal 
nature  over  the  soul.  Hence  inward  chastity  is  above  all 
things  necessary.  And  this  requires  the  suppression  of  impure 
images  that  arise  in  the  mind,  and  easily  lead  to  impure 
desires,  or  to  "  alaxpoXoyia"  (Eph.  v.  3,  iv.  22  f.;  Col.  iii.  8  ; 
Matt.  XV.  11);  and  the  avoidance  of  wanton  pictures  and 
books.  Christian  chastity  also  demands  modesty  in  dress 
(1  Cor.  xi.  5;  Matt.  v.  8,  xv.  18 ;  1  Tim.  iv.  12,  v.  2; 
Acts  xxiv.  25  ;   1  Cor.  vi.  13-20). 

4.  Virtuous  heav.ty. — The  sphere  of  the  beautiful  and  of 
art  reaches  much  farther  than  art  pure  and  simple.  Every  one 
should  have  his  share  in  the  beautiful,  and  every  Christian 
does  have  it.  Nay,  the  idea  of  art — the  informing  of  the 
natural  by  the  ideal — is  much  more  perfectly  realized  where 
the  material  that  is  so  informed  is  a  person,  than  where  it  is 
marble  or  canvass  (%api9,  grace,  Eph.  iv.  29;  Col.  iv.  6). 
Now  it  looks,  indeed,  as  if  it  were  an  exaggeration  to  demand 
beauty  as  a  virtue,  and  many  are  fond,  in  this  connection, 
of  referring  to  Socrates.  But  yet  it  is  certain  that  the  body, 
especially  the  countenance  and  the  eye,  is  and  should  be  a 
mirror  that  reflects  the  character,  just  as  the  sway  of  evil, 
on  the  other  hand,  gives  the  body  an  ill-favoured  appearance. 
It  may,  indeed,  happen  that  a  man's  endowment  in  this 
respect  is  meagre  to  begin  with,  but  even  the  most  unpro- 
mising physiognomy  becomes  ennobled  by  nobility  of  mind. 
This  implies  that  when  we  speak  of  virtuous  beauty  we  cannot 


468         §  62.  VIRTUOUS  PURITY  AND  BEAUTY. 

mean  that  tempting  beauty  to  which  the  French,  with  some 
degree  of  frivolity  and  yet  not  without  puugency,  have  given 
the  name  of  "  beaute  de  diable,"  thus  indicating  those  attrac- 
tions which,  like  the  flowers,  have  their  time  to  bloom,  but 
also  like  them,  and  all  the  things  of  earth,  have  their  time  to 
fade.  No,  we  mean  that  beauty  which  lasts  and  can  increase 
with  age,  which  can  be  displayed  not  merely  in  face  and 
figure,  but  also  in  glance  and  mien,  in  bearing  and  behaviour, 
as  well  as  in  grace  and  charm  of  speech.  In  woman,  the 
essential  character  of  this  beauty,  that  does  not  wither  but 
increases  with  age,  is  grace, — and  this  can  be  exhibited  even 
when  the  body  is  not  beautiful  by  nature ;  in  man  it  is 
dignity.  And  in  both  cases,  each  sex,  starting  with  its  own 
characteristic  beauty,  should  appropriate  to  itself  the  excellence 
peculiar  to  the  other.  Thus  the  beauty  of  woman  becomes  in 
old  a^e  that  of  the  dignified  matron,  while  on  the  other  side 
we  have  the  beauty  of  the  kindly  old  man.  Virtuous  beauty, 
moreover,  should  not  be  exhibited  in  personal  appearance  only, 
but  also  in  dress  and  in  the  liomc  (1  Pet.  iii.  1  ff.).  Here,  too, 
the  aesthetic  principle  should  receive  its  due  place.  In  con- 
sequence of  the  progress  of  humanity,  inventions  of  many 
kinds,  such  as  photography,  have  made  art  a  good  much 
more  within  reach  of  all,  and  introduced  it  into  family  life. 
We  should  preserve  a  style  of  living  suitable  to  our  position  ; 
personal  honour  demands  that  in  this  connection,  too,  the  out- 
ward appearance  should  be  dignified  and  pleasing.  But  too 
much  importance  ought  not  to  be  attached  to  it,  as  if  the  coat 
made  the  man.  Slavish  dependence  upon  fashion  is  a  weak- 
ness, indicating  emptiness  of  head  and  hollowness  of  heart. 
Among  our  own  people,  along  with  the  breaking  up  of 
corporations,  etc.,  a  levelling  process  even  in  respect  of  dress 
(the  so-called  French  costume)  has  come  in  with  the  dress-coat. 
But  Ethics  must  insist  upon  this — that  countless  evils  and 
miseries  now  existing  amongst  us  will  not  give  way  until 
more  truth  is  introduced  into  dres.s,  until  it  is  more  in  keep- 
ing with  personal  position.  And  this  can  only  happen  by  the 
masses  once  more  organizing  themselves,  and  of  their  ov;n 
free-will  forming  a  standard  of  honour  and  of  custom  for  the 
various  ranks  of  life.  A  general  custom  thus  established 
would   afford    the   individual   direction   and   a   fixed  line   of 


CHRISTIAN  MANAGEMENT  OF  PROPERTY.  46  9 

conduct  to  be  pursued  with  regard  to  liis  expenditure  in 
general,  and  his  dress  in  particular.  This  leads  us  to  the 
subject  of  luxury.  It  is  true,  in  a  general  sense,  that  it  is  not 
only  what  is  indispensable  and  necessary  that  is  morally 
permissible,  and  this  altogether  apart  from  custom,  which 
demands  of  the  higher  classes  a  certain  degree  of  luxury  in 
their  household  arrangements.  The  a3Sthetic  principle  may 
also  be  carried  out  in  one's  own  house ;  everything  is  not  to 
depend  on  mere  economy.  And  here,  it  is  not  only  comfort, 
in  the  strict  sense  of  the  word,  or  convenience,  that  has  to  be 
attended  to,  but  also  the  exhibition  of  taste,  and  this  demands 
a  certain  measure  of  profusion.  God  Himself  has  so  con- 
stituted the  world  that  not  only  herbage,  but  also  flowers  grow 
upon  the  meadows  (John  xii.  1-8,  ii.  1-12).  But  in  this 
matter,  too,  the  Christian  spirit  must  be  expressed.  And  we 
manifest  it,  when  we  do  not  allow  our  hearts  to  cleave  to 
luxury,  when  it  does  not  tend  to  effeminate  us  or  encourage 
impure  fancy,  and  when,  if  need  be,  we  are  willing  to  sacrifice 
luxury  for  the  sake  of  the  community  or  of  our  suffering 
brethren.-^ 

§  63.  Conclusion. 

Virhious  OiunersTiip,  or  Christian  Management  of  Property. 

1.  The  possession  of  property  is  also  necessary  to  the 
dignity  of  the  Christian  personality,  because  it  enables  the 
Christian  to  take  his  share  in  the  subjugation  of  the  world, 
which  is  one  of  the  tasks  assigned  to  our  race.  It  is  the 
duty  of  a  man  to  have  property,  and  he  who  renounces  it 
renounces  important  ethical  functions.  For  it  is  altogether 
inconceivable  that  one  wdio  had  absolutely  no  property  should 
achieve  anything  in  the  various  moral  spheres ;  he  would  be 
extremely  ill-provided,  both  as  to  material  and  means  of  dis- 
playing his  activity,  if  he  possessed  nothing  belonging  to  the 
kingdom  of  nature  but  his  own  body.  On  the  other  hand, 
the  property  he  acquires  for  the  purposes  of  bodily  life  or  of 
his  calling,  is  the  first  thing  to  give  an  extension  to  his  mere 
corporeal  existence,  just  as  the  earth  is,  in  a  wider  sense,  the 
body  of  the  race.  Fidelity  is  demanded  even  in  the  things 
of  earth  (Luke  xvi.  1  f . ;  Matt  xxv.  14-30).     Acquisition  of 

{}  See  in  addition  the  following  paragraph.] 


470  §  C3.  CONCLUSION. 

property  is  a  duty  (2  Thess.  iii.  12  ;  Epli.  iv.  28) ;  but  only  as 
a  mediate,  not  as  an  alDSolute  aim.  The  efforts  put  forth  by 
the  Christian  to  become  a  possessor  of  property  must  be  noUe 
in  their  purpose  or  ultimate  end,  and  conscientious  in  the 
choice  of  the  means  to  be  employed.  Now,  the  goodness  of 
our  aims  depends  upon  the  use  to  which  we  put  what  we 
acquire,  and  this  should  be  {a)  to  support  those  who  belong- 
to  us,  and  (h)  to  relieve  poverty  and  aid  the  general  interests 
of  the  kingdom  of  God.  The  moral  quality  which  has  to  do 
with  the  preservation  of  property  is  frugality  as  opposed  to 
cxtravarjance,  that  which  is  taken  up  with  its  augmentation 
is  industry  as  opposed  to  negligence.  Niggardliness  is  not  an 
excess  of  the  virtue  of  frugality,  and  covetousness  is  not  an 
excess  of  the  virtue  of  industry.  On  the  contrary,  although 
in  appearance  they  differ  only  in  degree,  yet  internally,  as 
far  as  regards  motive  and  disposition,  frugality  and  industry 
on  the  one  hand,  and  niggardliness  and  covetousness  on  the 
other,  are  as  different  from  each  other  as  virtue  and  vice.  The 
latter  make  the  mere  earthly  possession  their  sole  aim,  while 
the  former  seek  to  obtain  it  as  a  means  to  be  employed  by 
the  spirit,  and  for  the  service  of  the  moral  kingdom.  Those 
who  display  niggardliness  and  avarice  think  they  will  acquire 
more  personal  worth,  more  power  and  freedom.  But  here  we 
see  how  sadly  sin  deceives  its  friends ;  for  they  are  made  all 
the  more  dependent  upon  the  world,  upon  what  is  earthly. 
Since  they  give  their  whole  souls  to  worldly  gain,  they  make 
it  the  satisfaction  of  their  spiritual  needs,  their  highest  good 
as  it  were,  even  their  God  (1  Tim.  vi.  6-10  ;  Matt.  vi.  19-22  ; 
1  Cor.  vii.  30,  31).  But  the  Christian  preserves  his  freedom, 
since  he  does  not  cleave  absolutely  and  therefore  immovably 
to  what  he  possesses,  as  if  it  were  the  supreme  good ;  he  has 
as  though  he  had  not,  he  has  his  treasure  Avithin  himself,  and 
having  it  he  is  independent  of  all  externals  (Col.  iii,  5  ;  Eph. 
V.  3,  5).         ^     _ 

2.  The  Collisions  ■wJiich  the  stand2')oint  of  Plight  (per  se  Private 
Bight)  introduces  into  the  Sj)here  of  Property  (cf.  §  3  oft).  At 
an  earlier  stage  (§  17,  cf.  §  18),  we  considered  the  beginnings 
of  Property.  Man,  as  the  being  in  the  likeness  of  God,  has  it 
as  his  right  and  his  vocation  to  take  possession  of  the  earth 
(Gen.  i.  28),  and  to  impress  upon  it  the  stamp  of  his  dominion. 


COLLISIONS  IN  THE  SPHERE  OF  PEOPERTY.  471 

But  this  is  first  of  all  the  right  and  duty  of  mankind  as  a  whole. 
How  then  does  the  individual  come  to  hold  property  exclusively  ? 
or  how  does  it  happen  that  what  belongs  to  one,  just  for  that 
reason  does  it  not  belong  to  another  ?  This  is  only  possible 
by  means  of  the  idea  of  right,  which  makes  what  we  possess 
to  be  our  property  (§  33a).  It  is  the  idea  of  Rigid  that 
determines  how  that  work  of  occupying  and  ruling  the  whole 
earth,  which  is  incumbent  upon  mankind,  is  to  be  carried  out. 
Property  necessarily  arises  in  the  following  way.  The 
individual  takes  possession  of  some  one  thing,  some  part  of 
nature,  which  he  occupies,  makes  serviceable  to  his  will,  and 
upon  which  he  expends  his  labour.  What  a  man  has  thus 
appropriated  and  occupied,  and  on  this  ground  has  made  the 
object  of  moral  exertion,  cannot  be  seized  upon  by  another 
without  violation  of  right ;  the  latter  must  recognise  the  prior 
right  of  the  former.  Thus  Paul  was  resolved,  even  with 
reference  to  his  spiritual  avocation  (Pom.  xv.  20),  "not  to 
enter  upon  another  man's  labours."  It  is  a  sin  "  to  encroach 
upon  another  man's  office"  (1  Pet.  iv.  15).  Hence  the  right 
to  private  property  is  a  well-established  one,  and  includes 
also  the  right  to  dispose  of  it,  e.g.  by  sale,  exchange,  presenta- 
tion, or  by  legacies  and  wills.  And  here  it  is  to  be  specially 
noted,  that  the  property  of  a  person  who  is  dead  passes  of 
itself  to  his  family,  without  a  will  (succession  by  law), 
because  the  possession  of  property  by  an  individual  member 
of  a  family  involves  the  right  of  the  family  to  an  eventual 
claim  upon  it.  It  is,  however,  only  too  true  that  the 
right  of  property  is  accompanied  with  much  injustice  and 
sin.  Wealth  may  be  polluted  by  being  wrongfully  obtained, 
or  through  injustice  of  a  coarse  or  more  refined  kind,  and 
nevertheless  pass  lawfully  from  hand  to  hand,  e.g.  may  be 
inherited.  The  distribution  of  wealth  may  in  the  course  of 
history  arrive  at  a  condition  in  which,  wliile  one  person  is 
excessively  rich,  another  is  shamefully  poor,  and  has  not  even 
so  much  as  the  means  of  self-culture  or  of  moral  activity.  It 
was  in  anticipation  of  such  evils  that  the  Old  Testament 
instituted  the  Sabbatical  year,  the  year  of  Jubilee,  and  other 
laws,  with  the  purpose  of  restoring  a  healthy  condition  of  things 
by  means  of  a  fixed  and  regular  adjustment  of  property. 
These    evils   increase  like   an   avalanche   as    if  by  a  law  of 


472  §  63.  CONCLUSION. 

gravitation  ;  the  greater  mass  of  wealth,  as  it  now  exists,  has 
a  greater  attractive  power,  and  Right,  which  gives  to  what  we 
possess  its  higher  meaning  and  consecration,has  so  little  power  to 
avert  these  evils,  that  it  rather  serves  to  perpetuate  the  wrong 
and  sinful  way  in  which  wealtli  is  divided  between  the  rich 
and  the  poor.  For  right  merely  gives  security  to  property 
and  the  differences  that  exist  in  its  division — as  it  finds  them. 
It  is  not  productive,  it  cannot  create  a  right  distribution 
of  wealth  by  its  own  power.  It  is  only  divine  justice  that 
can  do  this,  that  justitia  distributiva,  which  is  essential  wis- 
dom directed  by  love.  Thus  things  may  arrive  at  such  a  state, 
that  right  becomes  the  servant  of  Egoism,  and  the  rich  are 
established  by  Divine  right  in  the  possession  of  property  to 
the  exclusion  of  the  poor,  wdiereas  God  gave  the  earth  to  man, 
not  to  the  rich.  We  are  here  presented  with  a  serious 
antinomy,  viz.,  that  an  unrighteous  state  of  matters,  such  as 
this  unjust  distribution  of  wealth,  is  confirmed  by  a  Divine  idea, 
the  idea  of  right.  This  antinomy  cannot  be  resolved  from  the 
simple  standpoint  of  right.  For  right  even  in  its  law-making 
capacity,  although  it  may  introduce  to  some  degree  an  adjust- 
ment with  regard  to  the  future,  must  not  go  the  length  of 
plundering  the  property  of  an  individual,  nor  reduce  the 
individual  personality  to  a  state  of  pupilage.  The  function  of 
the  state  is  simply  to  protect  personal  freedom  and  the  possi- 
bility of  personal  development.  It  must  not  take  the  first 
result  of  free  activity,  the  acquirement  of  property,  out  of  the 
hands  of  individuals ;  it  must  not  constitute  itself  a  uni- 
versal guardian  and  manager  of  wealth ;  this  would  be  con- 
trary to  its  right  and  duty.  It  must  not  make  a  division  of 
wealth, — by  giving  the  same  to  each,  for  instance  ;  this  would 
be  to  offer  a  premium  to  idleness,  and  to  impose  a  punish- 
ment upon  industry  and  skill  A  similar  result  would  ensue 
were  families  not  allowed  to  keep  an  inheritance,  a  property 
that  had  been  gained :  this  would  discourage  individual 
spirit  and  industry.  A  succession-duty  is  alone  permissible. 
Otherwise,  the  united  work  of  mankind  would  be  interrupted 
in  revolutionary  fashion.  Humanity  would  become  a  mass  of 
drones,  and  a  universal  moral  corruption  and  chaos  would 
soon  intervene.  Even  progressive  taxation,  which  might  render 
some  help  to  an  adjustment,  would,  if  it  were  to  encroach  too 


MODIFICATION  OF  THE  IDEA  OF  PEOPEETY.  473 

far,  pamper  laziness  and  discourage  the  spirit  of  enterprise — 
and  this  is  a  leading  argument  against  the  modern  theories  of 
Comvuvnism  and  Socialism.  The  enforcement  of  poor-rates  is 
also  unable  to  remove  the  evil  thoroughly;  nor  is  any  system  of 
Political  Economy  adequate  to  the  problem.  Here,  therefore, 
we  again  see  clearly  enough  the  powerlessness  of  Eight  to  occupy 
the  highest  place.  Unless  it  relies  upon  other  spiritual  powers 
besides  itself,  it  cannot  even  make  it  possible  for  every  man 
freely  to  develop  his  personal  life.  It  is  love  and  wisdom 
alone  which,  without  injury  to  right,  can  go  back  to  fulfil  the 
original  will  of  God,  according  to  which  it  is  manhind,  and  not  a 
part  of  it  or  only  some  individuals,  that  is  to  possess  the  earth 
— that  Divine  will  which  cannot  be  realized  by  Eight  alone, 
whether  in  its  private  or  public  form,  since,  in  order  to  avoid 
a  chaos,  it  must  rather  serve  as  the  protector  of  Mammon. 
Christianity  found  proprietorship  grown  stiff  and  exclusive  ;  it 
made  it  again  free  and  mobile,  broke  down  its  inflexibility, 
and  softened  the  rigidity  of  right  by  first  of  all  relaxing  it  in 
the  heart  of  the  owner  himself. 

o.  Modification  of  the  idea  of  Property  hy  Christianity. 
There  is  a  difference  here  between  the  Old  Testament  and  the 
New.  It  was  a  temporal  future  that  was  set  before  Israel. 
The  Holy  Land  had  for  the  Israelites  a  religious  significance. 
Their  possessions,  distributed  according  to  tribes  and  families, 
were,  like  the  people  itself,  God's  property.  It  was  not 
merely  a  right  but  a  duty,  for  each  family  to  hold  a  piece  of 
property  in  subjection  to  Jehovah.  And  this  was  not  to  be 
for  ever  alienated  from  a  family.  The  Christian  religion  has 
no  connection  with  any  particular  land.  The  promise  of 
earthly  blessing  to  the  pious  falls  into  the  background  behind 
the  promise  of  salvation,  and  even  as  compared  with  the 
granting  of  spiritual  blessings  in  the  present.  But  Chris- 
tianity does  not  help  to  solve  the  problem  by  destroying  the 
idea  of  property,  and  inviting  men  to  a  distribution  of  goods 
under  some  such  banner  as  that  of  Liberty,  Equality,  and 
Fraternity.  Nor  does  it  merely  demand  the  establishment  of 
a  state  of  things  in  which  all  shall  possess  the  same  amount. 
It  is  wrong  to  adduce  the  Church  of  Jerusalem  as  a  proof  that 
Christianity  introduces  the  abolition  of  property  (Acts  iv.  32, 
V.  4).      It  was  love  that  then  put  property  at  common  dis- 


474  §  63.  CONCLUSION. 

posal  to  meet  the  needs  of  others.  Community  of  goods  was 
not  a  law,  it  was  not  universal.  Christianity  did  not  directly 
abolish  even  the  worst  species  of  property,  that  of  slaves,  nor 
did  it  prohibit  it  by  positive  laws.  But,  without  directly 
altering  anything  in  the  absolute  right  of  property  with 
respect  to  others,  without  demanding  of  the  legislature  a 
direct  change  in  favour  of  the  lower  classes,  Christianity 
simply  established  a  moral  and  religious  way  of  regarding 
property.  Property  has  been  given  by  God  ;  He  gives  it  every 
moment,  and  that  for  good  ends,  and  we  must  give  account  of 
how  we  use  it.  That  is  to  say,  that  which  in  relation  to  men 
is  the  right  of  property,  is,  when  looked  at  from  a  religious 
point  of  view,  or  in  relation  to  God,  only  the  right  of 
administration  of  a  good,  not  our  oivn,  hut  entrusted  to  our  care 
(1  Pet,  iv.  10).  Man  only  holds  it  in  fee  from  God,  there- 
fore for  good  and  Divine  ends.  Consequently,  when  he 
dissociates  it  from  these  ends,  and  uses  it  selfishly,  he  thereby 
robs  God  of  what  is  His  ;  from  being  a  steward  he  becomes  an 
embezzler,  although  no  one  of  his  fellow-men  has  a  right  to 
take  his  goods  from  him  because  he  does  not  use  them  faith- 
fully. For  the  right  of  stewardship  is  with  respect  to  others 
nevertheless  a  right ;  to  them  he  remains  a  proprietor,  as  long 
as  the  lord  of  the  house  does  not  take  his  office  from  him 
(Luke  xvi.  ;  Matt.  xxi.  3  3  f .).  To  this  lord  he  is  only  faithful 
in  his  stewardship,  if  he  uses  his  good  as  the  giver  intended. 
But  God,  when  He  imparts  to  an  individual  anything  of  which 
he  is  to  have  the  management,  does  not  have  regard  solely  to 
him,  although  it  is  meant  to  be  a  blessing  to  him  also 
(Ps.  cxii.  3,  xxxiv.  10;  Prov.  iii.  16,  viii.  18,  x.  22;  Deut. 
xxviii.  2-8).  God's  purpose  is  never  confined  to  an  isolated 
individual,  but  includes  the  whole  community.  But  at  the 
same  time,  this  general  purpose  is  to  be  wrought  out  through 
the  free-will  of  the  individual.  Thus  the  right  of  property  is 
preserved  uninjured,  while  scope  is  given  for  softening  the 
rigid  harshness  of  laws  relating  to  private  right,  and  making 
compensation  for  inequalities  that  are  becoming  notorious. 
But  it  is  the  spirit  of  free-love  that  does  the  work.  Here 
accordingly  we  have  the  grounds  of  the  ethical  right  of  the 
church  to  the  care  of  the  poor,  of  the  diaconate,  which  as 
early  as  Acts  vi.  appears  as  one  of  the  earliest  of  Church 


UNEQUAL  DISTEIBUTION  OF  PEOPERTY.  475 

institutions,  and  of  the  Inner  Mission,  the  many  ramifications 
of  which  embrace,  both  in  a  fixed  official  manner  and  also 
freely,  the  whole  sphere  of  Christian  and  national  life. 

The  unequal  distribution  of  property  rests,  undoubtedly, 
upon  a  Divine  order  [talents  being  unequal  to  begin  with,  the 
acquisitions  made  by  their  use  must  be  different;  cf.  p.  509] 
(Prov.  xxii.  2;  Eccles.  ix.  11  f.;  1  Sam.  ii.  7;  John  xii.  8). 
But  in  order  to  incite  lis  to  communicative  love,  Christianity 
also  warns  us  of  the  dangers  of  riches.  The  essential  equality 
of  all  men,  which  Christianity  proclaims,  nay,  realizes  (1  John 
V.  1),  takes  away  the  chief  support  of  the  separation  between 
rich  and  poor ;  but  also  makes  Christianity  a  stumbling- 
block  to  Egoism,  and  occasions  a  crisis,  in  which  the  rich  are 
exposed  to  greater  danger  than  the  poor  (Luke  vi.  24  ;  Matt. 
xix.  21  f.).  Since  the  blessings  which  Christianity  confers 
involve  the  essential  equality  of  all  men  (Gal.  iii.  28),  and 
mitigate  from  within  outwards  the  sharpness  of  the  difference 
l)etween  rich  and  poor ;  since,  too,  the  charitable  duty  of 
giving  to  the  poor  is  incumbent  upon  the  rich,  it  naturally 
follows  that  it  is  harder  for  the  rich  to  become  Christians,  and 
that  it  demands  more  self-denial  on  their  part  (cf.  Matt. 
xix.  21  f,  the  rich  young  man).  In  addition  to  this,  wealth 
soon  makes  us  satisfied  and  proud,  increases  worldliness  and 
worldly  desires,  and  conceals  from  us  our  spiritual  poverty. 
Accordingly  we  find  such  passages  as  Luke  vi.  24,  "Woe  to 
you  that  are  rich,"  which  is  not  a  curse,  but  a  lamentation 
(cf.  Luke  xvi.  19  f ,  xii.  16  f.  ;  Jas.  v.  1  f.).  So,  too,  the  desire 
to  become  rich  (1  Tim.  vi.  6-10  ;  Prov.  xxiii.  4,  xxviii.  22), 
instead  of  contentment  (xxx.  8),  is  described  as  a  snare ;  and 
in  Matt.  xix.  23  f.,  Mark  x.  23,  Luke  xviii.  25,  it  is  said  of 
the  rich,  that  it  is  harder  for  them  to  enter  into  the  kingdom 
of  heaven  than  for  a  camel  to  go  through  the  eye  of  a  needle. 
But  in  exchange  for  what  is  given  up,  Christianity  gives  new 
riches,  which  are  none  the  smaller  because  all  men,  even  the 
poor,  may  possess  them.  In  the  case  of  the  Church  of 
Jerusalem,  it  was  a  natural  expression  given  by  Christians 
of  their  sense  of  the  new  riches  they  had  found,  when  to  a 
certain  degree  they  had  all  things  in  common.  Xot  that  the 
renunciation  of  property  would  be  in  itself  a  virtue  ;  we 
might  thereby  renounce  also  our  vocation,  our  stewardship. 


476  §  63.  CONCLUSION- 

But  the  Christian  in  his  freedom  can  be  at  once  rich  and  poor 
(Phil.  iv.  11,  12).  Tliis  inward  freedom  from  the  fetters  of 
wealth,  and  from  its  temptations,  found  expression  in  that 
sense  of  common  interests,  which  made  the  early  Christians 
put  all  their  property  at  the  disposal  of  the  wliole  community 
for  the  ends  of  the  kingdom  of  God  (Acts  iv.  32  ff.,  v,  4j. 

4.  It  was  the  Church  first,  and  afterwards  the  civil  com- 
munity and  the  State,  which  took  charge  of  the  poor ;  in 
the  latter  case,  however,  poverty  increases.  In  the  Catholic 
Church,  care  of  the  poor,  through  the  influence  of  the  erroneous 
doctrine  of  justification  by  works,  gave  rise  to  begging,  a 
practice  that  was  repressed  by  the  Old  Testament,  that 
personal  dignity  might  not  be  injured  (Deut.  xv.  4)  :  "  There 
shall  be  no  beggar  among  you."  Such  was  to  be  the  result 
of  care  of  the  poor.  And  it  is  possible  to  secure  it  by  distin- 
guishing the  various  kinds  of  poverty.  These  are  (1)  Wilftil 
poverty  arising  from  laziness.  (2)  Unmerited  poverty  from 
physical  causes.      (3)  Social  poverty. 

V/ilful  poverty,  where  a  man  will  not  work,  must  be 
repressed  by  the  State,  by  its  police  and  by  punishment ; 
here  the  apostolic  saying  holds  good — "  He  who  will  not 
work,  neither  shall  he  eat  "  (Eph.  iv.  28  ;  cf.  1  Thess.  iv.  11 ; 
2  Thess.  iii.  10,  12;  Ex.  xx.  9).  There  is  no  obligation  on 
the  part  of  State  or  Cliurch  to  feed  the  lazy.  It  is  only  in 
the  way  of  furnishing  work  that  both  of  them  have  to  provide 
for  poverty.  And  this  preserves  the  dignity  of  a  man,  which 
will  make  him  willing  to  eat  his  own  bread.  The  sick, 
orphans  and  widows,  etc.,  should  be  provided  for  without 
having  to  beg,  by  means  appointed  by  the  Church  for  the 
care  of  the  poor. 

Those  who  are  socially  poor,  wlio  desire  work  but  cannot 
find  it,  must  be  provided  for  by  the  state  and  conmiunity,  in 
connection  with  voluntary  associations  for  that  purpose.  The 
state  must  also  act  by  legislation. 

Note  1. — Socialism  and  Covmmnism. 

The  Literature. — Stein,  Dcr  Socialismus  und  Communismus 
dcs  hcutigcn  Franhrcich,  2nd  ed.  1848,  pp.  574-590.  Litera- 
ture on  this  subject.  Engels,  Die  Lage  dcr  arheitenden  Klassen 
in  England.  1845.  Quintessence  of  Socialism.  Alexander 
Meyer,  Der  Emancipationskampf  des  vierten  Standes.     Wichern, 


SOCIALISM  AND  COMMUNISM.  477 

Vortrag  auf  dcr  OJdoberconferenz,  1872.  v.  Treitzsclike,  Dcr 
Socialisnius  und  seine  Gonner.  Freussische  Jahrhucher,  vol.  xxxiv. 
part  I.  Schmoller,  Ueder  cinige  Gruiidfragen  des  Beclits  und  dcr 
Volksicirtlischaft.  1875.  JNIartensen's  Ethics  (Clark's  transla- 
tion), vol.  ii.  p.  142  fF.  Lasselle,  System  dcr  crivorhcncn  Ecclite. 
Marx,  Das  Capital.  Scliteffle,  Capitalisonus  und  Socialisnius, 
2nd  ed.  1878.  [Eeischl,  Arhcitcrfrage  nnd  Socialisnius.  1874. 
L.  Brentano,  Das  Arhcitsvcrh'dltniss  genidss  dcni  hcutigcn  Rcchtc. 
1877.  E.  Owen :  A  list  of  his  writings  is  given  in  Eeyband's 
Etudes  sicr  les  reformatcurs  contcniporains.  Lange,  Die  Arhcitcr- 
frage. 1875.  Cf.  also  Uhlhorn,  Die  cJiristliche  Lichcsthdtigkeit  in 
dcr  cdtcn  Kirclie,  im  Mittelcdtcr.  Wach,  Die  christlich  socicde 
Arhcitcrpartci.  Dove,  Die  Vcrwcrthung  dcr  Kirchcngcmcinde 
und  Sjjnodcdinstitutioncn  zur  Losung  dcr  socicdcn  Aufgahen. 
(Eeport  at  the  German  Evangelical  Church  Conference.)  A. 
Dorner,  Kirche  und  Beich  Gottcs,  pp.  363  f.  Hartmann,  Phdno- 
mcnologie  des  sittlichen  Beivusstscins,  pp.  589-652.  Cf.  Eoscher, 
Gcscliichte  dcr  Nationcd-dkonomie  in  Dcutschland,  especially 
pp.  1004  f.] 

The  development  of  national  industries  that  has  taken 
place  in  more  recent  times  has  been  the  cause  of  a  great 
inequality  in  wealth,  while  the  enormous  extension  of  manu- 
factures especially,  has  given  capital  the  control  of  labour — a 
state  of  things  that  has  given  rise  to  pauperism  and  pro- 
letarianism.  Parallel  with  this  state  of  things,  there  has 
been  a  hitherto  unheard-of  increase  of  the  self-consciousness 
of  the  lower  classes,  in  consequence  especially  of  the  French 
Eevolution,  with  its  proclamation  of  the  equality  and  liberty 
of  the  individual.  An  equal  share  in  wealth  and  the  enjoy- 
ments of  life  is  demanded  as  a  universal  right  of  man,  at 
one  time  by  theories  which  are  indigenous  to  France  especially, 
at  another,  by  action  in  the  way  of  revolutions  and  strikes, 
and  also  by  more  rational  means.  The  most  important 
socialists  in  France  are  St.  Simon  and  Fourier  and  their  school ; 
Pierre  Leroux,  de  la  Mennais,  Proudhon  and  Louis  Blanc ; 
in  England,  Jeremy  Bentham,  E.  Owen,  and  Stuart  Mill,  who 
is  of  kindred  spirit  (cf.  his  Life,  1874).  Communism  made  its 
appearance  during  the  first  French  Eevolution  in  the  person 
of  Babeuf,  spread  more  widely  after  the  revolution  of  July 
(Cabet,  Voyage  en  Icaric),  until  in  1870  and  1871  it  for  a  time 
obtained  full  sway  in  Paris.  Socialism  and  Communism  have 
also  been  propagated  in  Germany,  especially  by   Marx  and 


478  §  63.  CONCLUSION. 

Lasselle.  It  was  in  England  that  workmen  first  sought  to 
extort  higher  wages  by  forming  imions  and  strikes  in  opposition 
to  employers,  but  in  this  way  they  have  only  injured  themselves 
and  the  national  prosperity.  In  the  so-called  Chartism  ^  they 
proceeded  to  enforce  their  wishes  in  a  legal  way,  through 
Parliament  and  Parliamentary  elections.  In  like  manner, 
among  ourselves,  Lasselle  looks  to  state  aid  to  carry  out  his 
ideas,  and  in  this  way  he  is  opposed  to  Schultze-Delitzsch, 
whose  watchword  is  self-help  on  the  part  of  working-men  by 
means  of  associations.  Communism  seeks,  in  the  supposed 
interests  of  freedom  and  equality,  to  abolish  personal  property 
for  ever  and  in  every  form."  There  is  also  to  be  no  such  thing 
as  subordination,  not  even  such  as  arises  in  a  republic  from 
the  common  will  of  the  people.  Every  one  is  to  have  a  claim 
to  everything,  and  this  idea  is  also  extended  to  community  of 
wives,  etc.  From  the  emphasis  it  lays  upon  liberty  and 
equality,  it  seems  to  be  inclined  to  republicanism  ;  nevertheless 
it  is  essentially  anarchical,  because  even  a  republic  demands 
subordination  of  the  individual  will  to  the  general  will  of  the 
state.  Communism  destroyes  the  state ;  it  will  not  even  let 
civil  society  stand,  as  Socialism  does.  The  latter  only  aims 
at  a  better  constitution  of  society  with  regard  to  the  division 
of  labour  and  property,  at  an  organization  of  labour,  but  still 
undoubtedly  on  the  principle  of  equality,  and  therefore  also 
in  a  chimerical  manner,  because  inequalities  would  necessarily 
ensue  from  the  inequality  of  individuals,  in  talents,  in  industry, 
and  in  honesty.  Both  Communism  and  Socialism  involve  the 
assumption  that  the  Divine  right  of  every  man  is  the  same  ; 
both  are  manifestations  of  Individualism  —  fragments  or 
caricatures  of  the  Reformation  principle,  which  civilized 
Erance,  while  remaining  Catholic,  has  managed  to  pick  up. 
Both  talk  of  rights,  not  of  duties ;  and  rights  are  conceived  in  a 
2mrely  eudcemonistic  form  [labour  is  essentially  regarded  only 
as  a  means  to  enjoyment].  For  the  most  part  they  hate  all 
religion,  deny  God  and  immortality,  and  hold  that  the  chief 
good  is   to  be   found    in    the    present    world,   in   the   grati- 

^  [On  tlie  Chartist  movement,  cf.  the  article  by  L.  Brentano,  Preussische 
Jahrhilcher,  May,  June,  1874 ;  and  Gammage,  History  of  the  Chartist 
Movement.'\ 

-  Stein,  I.e.  p.  446. 


SOCIALISM  AND  COMMUNISM,  479 

fication  of  desire.  At  the  same  time,  however,  they  are  fond 
of  talking  as  if  they  only  wanted  to  realize  the  aspirations 
of  the  Church  of  Jerusalem,  and  accordingly,  to  their 
watchwords,  freedom  and  equality,  they  have  added  another — 
fraternity.  Of  the  socialists  especially  is  this  the  case.  But 
the  difference  lies  here :  the  primitive  Church,  animated  by 
love,  desired  to  give  to  each  a  share  of  the  general  wealth, 
those  who  had  property  supplying  those  who  had  none 
according  to  their  need;  whereas  socialists  desire  to  take 
each  his  share.  In  the  latter  case  we  have  egoism,  coming 
into  conflict  with  right ;  in  the  former  love,  raising  us  above 
the  stage  of  law,  law  being  admittedly  inadequate  to  meet  the 
collisions  that  have  arisen. 

The  great  evil  from  which  society  is  suffering  may  forebode 
a  helium  intestinum,  such  as  was  the  Servile  War  in  ancient 
Eome.  It  cannot  be  remedied  by  any  panacea  —  e.g.  by 
societies  or  political  rights,  or  by  any  one  ethical  sphere  apart 
from  others,  whether  State  or  Church  or  Inner  Mission ;  but 
all  must  work  together  in  a  free  and  legitimate  way  (the  way 
in  which  the  Inner  Mission  has  taken  up  this  work^),  State, 
Church,  the  Community,  voluntary  associations  and  individuals 
as  well.  But  one  thing  especially  will  be  necessary.  The 
breaking  up  of  the  organization  of  the  artisan  and  labouring 
classes  due  to  the  abolition  of  corporations,  the  introduction  of 
free  emigration  rights  and  a  universal  election  franchise,  has 
begun,  on  the  one  hand,  to  reduce  society  to  one  level,  and  on 
the  other,  altogether  to  effect  its  disintegration.  It  is  there- 
fore necessary  that  labour  should  be  reorganized,  and  his 
appointed  place  thus  allotted  to  each,  in  order  that  men  may 
not  foolishly  act  as  if  each  of  them  were  the  whole  community 
in  himself,  and  had  a  right  to  everything  ;  also  that  no  attempts 
should  be  made  to  bring  all  men  to  the  same  social  level  (which 
is  just  as  disorganizing),  but  that  each  one  should  have  his  place 
in  the  organism,  as  a  member  of  it, — differently  constituted 
indeed  from  other  members,  but  still  co-operating  towards  the 
general  welfare,  and  in  this  way  enabled  to  prosper  as  a  part 
of  the  whole.  Accordingly,  apprentices  must  be  trained,  pro- 
gressive training  schools  instituted,  and  the  difference  between 
masters,  journeymen,  and  apprentices  established. 

'  [Cf.  the  author'.?  address  at  the  Inner  Mission  Conference  in  Magdeburg.] 


480     §  G4.  SELF-LOVE  WITH  RESPECT  TO  THE  MENTAL  LIFE. 

Note  2.  Interest. — Cf.  Joh.  Dav.  Michaelis,  Mosaisclies  RecM, 
iii.  §  147  f.  ;  Luke  vi.  34  f. ;  Matt.  v.  42.  Aristotle  was  opposed 
to  interest ;  Cato,  too  (who,  however,  is  said  to  have  been  a 
usurer  himself).  In  the  Christian  Church  it  was  at  first 
regarded  as  unbecoming  in  clerics  to  engage  in  worldly  matters 
of  commerce,  and  accordingly  they  were  forbidden  to  accept 
interest.  But  this  prohibition  was  soon  extended  to  the  laity ; 
numerous  councils  and  popes  condemned  the  taking  of  interest 
as  contrary  to  the  command  of  God  in  the  Old  Testament,  and 
to  the  precept  of  Christ — to  lend  or  give  to  him  who  asks, 
demanding  nothing  in  return  (Luke  vi.  34 ;  Matt.  v.  42). 
However,  it  was  only  the  name  that  was  changed.  For  it 
was  not  reckoned  sinful  to  purchase  annuities  (rents,  yearly 
revenues),  to  let  houses,  or  to  lease  estates.  Escobar  even 
directs  that  in  money  matters  we  should  reserve  a  fixed  sum  for 
ourselves  under  the  title  of  a  sliare  in  the  profit,  and  only  avoid 
the  term  interest.  Hence  he  is  satirized  by  Pascal,  Salmasius, 
and  Molenteus.  Cf.  Eeinhard,  iii.  25  ff.  Boehraer,  Jus.  EccL, 
V.  pp.  330  ff.  The  Old  Testament  laws  are  not  binding  on  us, 
so  far  as  they  were  of  a  national  theocratic  kind.  Israel  was  to 
be  founded  not  upon  trade  and  intercourse  with  the  world,  but 
upon  agriculture.  The  merehant-spirit,  which  was  asleep  in 
Israel,  was  not  to  be  awakened.  The  Canaanite  merchant  was 
the  empirical,  worldly  Ego  of  Israel,  which  had  to  be  curbed  by 
the  law.  The  words  of  Christ,  moreover,  refer  to  Christian 
charity  towards  the  poor.  Christ  is  not  speaking  at  all  of  the 
case  where  one  uses  another's  money,  not  simply  to  relieve  his 
own  indigence,  but  to  make  profit  out  of  it.  On  the  other 
hand,  it  certainly  follows  from  His  words,  that  it  does  not 
become  a  Christian  to  be  severe  towards  the  poor,  much  less  to 
bring  them  to  ruin  by  the  demands  he  makes  with  regard  to 
either  interest  or  capital ;  in  such  cases  the  Christian  ought 
rather  to  be  willing  to  lose.  That  Christ  does  not  condemn  the 
taking  of  interest  is  evident  from  Matt.  xxv.  27. 

§  64. 

Self -Love  with  rcsjjeet  to  the  Mental  Life. 

2.  With  respect  to  the  Intellect  (§  58.  2),  Christian  self-love  is, 
on  the  side  of  Feeling  and  Cognition,  care  for  a  virtuous 
liberal  education,  while  on  the  side  of  the  Will  it  is 
care  for  virtuous  stability  of  character.  (Cf.  Eothe, 
FthiJc,  1st  ed.  iii.  pp.  250,  337.) 
1.  True  culture  embraces,  of  course,  whatever  is  ethical. 


TRUE  CULTURE.  481 

but  by  prevailing  usage  it  applies  more  to  the  culture  of  the 
understandmg  and  the  mind,  of  sensibility  and  taste.  At  the 
same  time,  hoAvever,  it  gives  a  polish  to  our  natural  instincts, 
although  it  in  no  way  enhances  their  intrinsic  value.  Educa- 
tion indicates  a  way  of  thinking  rather  than  a  way  or  system 
of  living,  although  there  is  no  doubt  that  true  culture  cannot 
exist  unless  the  will  too  is  pervaded  with  the  ethical  spirit. 

(a)  True  culture  consists  in  an  enlargement  of  our  mental 
horizon  beyond  the  narrow  individual  interests  of  person, 
position,  family,  city,  or  country ;  it  is  openness  of  mind  to 
the  idea  of  humanity  and  its  highest  interests.  In  this 
meaning  of  the  word,  humanism — a  sense  for  what  is  purely 
human — forms  one  side  of  the  Gospel  portraits  of  Christ,  a 
side  specially  brought  out  by  St.  Luke.  But  here  more 
accurate  definition  is  necessary. 

(/3)  True  culture  forms  as  great  a  contrast  to  that  vague 
cosmopolitanism,  which  has  no  home,  but  lives  in  a  world  of 
wholly  chaotic  and  elementary  ideals,  as  it  does  to  a  narrow 
I'hilistinism.  Abstract  universalism  is  just  as  much  a  per- 
version as  self-contained  individualism.  It  would  simply 
reduce  all  individuals  to  one  and  the  same  dead  level,  it 
would  smooth  away  all  personal  differences  in  a  characterless 
uniformity,  and  would  fatally  injure  the  idea  of  an  ethical 
organism,  by  breaking  it  up  as  it  were  into  atoms.  And  the 
individual  personality  would  also  be  injured  by  both  extremes 
alike ;  on  both  sides  there  is  about  an  equal  want  of  culture. 
No  doubt  it  is  on  its  culture  that  this  abstract  cosmopolitanism 
or  humanism  particularly  prides  itself,  as  we  see  from  its 
exponents,  who  are  to  be  found  more  especially  among 
literateurs  belonging  to  that  unfortunate  and  homeless  race, 
the  Jews,  and  among  the  discoverers  and  preachers  of  the 
rights  of  man.  It  points  out  how  the  barriers  that  separate 
different  classes  are  everywhere  falling  away,  and  how  the 
universal  solvent  of  culture  is  causing  everything  that  is 
fixed  and  rigid  to  disappear,  and  thus  bringing  men  closer  to 
each  other.  But  while  it  is  certain  that  progress  involves  as 
a  moment  the  breaking  up  and  decomposition  of  outlived 
institutions,  it  is  just  as  certain  that  such  an  equalization,  as 
is  here  spoken  of,  is  in  itself  so  unfruitful  and  poor  in  ideas 
that  it  requires  its  opposite  in  order  to  exist.     And  if  this 

2  II 


482  §  Cjl.    SELF-LOVE  WITH  RESPECT  TO  THE  MIND. 

Opposite  were  abolished,  there  would  exist  but  a  chaos,  a 
barbarism,  only  distinguished  from  that  barbarism  which  this 
innovating  tendency  reproaches  with  paleology  by  the  fact  that 
it  requires  a  universal  equality  of  individuals,  i.e.  an  equal 
barbarism  of  all.  Culture  must  not  resemble  a  faded  picture, 
but  be  like  a  diamond,  which  increases  by  polishing  in  the  sharp- 
ness of  its  angles  and  in  light  and  brilliancy.  Hence  we  are 
equally  in  opposition  to  true  culture  when,  adopting  this  merely 
negative  ideal,  whose  true  content  is  the  primitive  nothingness 
which  it  regards  as  Paradisaic,  we  surrender  ourselves  to  the 
desire  for  novelty  which  likes  to  be  called  Liberalism;  and  when 
wo  have  no  ideal  at  all,  but  are  satisfied  with  things  as  they  are 
(cf.  §  47  on  Optimism).  Christian  culture,  on  the  contrary, 
both  recognises  and  insists  on  personality,  to  which  the  indi- 
vidual and  general  factors  are  equally  important.  Christian 
culture  is  not  such  merely  general  humanity,  but  the  instilling 
of  the  general  interests  of  mankind  in  individuals, — a  process 
which  makes  them  bring  forth  fruit,  and  attain  to  a  condition 
whereby  the  entire  community  is  profited.  Or,  if  regarded  in 
a  personal  aspect,  it  is  a  development  of  our  inmost  nature, 
the  bringing  into  a  normal  state  our  natural  onesidedness  of 
temperament,  etc.  As  the  world,  however,  is  constituted,  the 
abstract  universal  and  the  abstract  particular  cannot  give  up 
their  contest  with  each  other ;  they  cannot  let  each  other  alone, 
nor — even  leaving  sin  out  of  the  question — be  really  recon- 
ciled, apart  from  that  higher  Christian  principle  which  unites 
them  by  placing  them  in  a  normal  state.  In  Christ  was 
manifested  true  universality,  true  humanity,  and  yet  in  a 
personal  form.  The  highest  Christian  aim  equally  excludes 
a  vague  generality,  which  is  but  empty  and  colourless,  and  a 
particularity  which  shows  itself  cold  and  reserved.  On  the 
contrary,  it  gives  intrinsic  worth  to  both  these  qualities,  which 
they  then  seek  and  find  in  each  other.  Empty  and  negative 
universality  seeks  both  to  be  filled  and  to  have  a  more 
concrete  definition,  and  lience  delights  in  and  desires  multi- 
plicity ;  cold  particularity,  when  its  view  and  interest  are 
expanded,  comes  to  its  truth,  and  desires  its  i^osition  as  a  single 
nicmher  of  an  organized  lodg.  And  this  involves  the  percep- 
tion of  its  own  limitation  ;  in  other  words,  modesty,  which  is 
an  essential  attribute  of  culture.     No  one  can  be  a  master  in 


VIRTUOUS  STABILITY.  483 

everything,  and  it  is  by  his  true  self-limitation  that  a  master 
is  known.  It  is,  moreover,  a  mark  of  an  uncultured  mind, 
to  have  no  appreciation  of,  or  feeling  for,  the  mastership  of 
others,  and,  by  rashly  giving  an  opinion  on  every  subject,  to 
credit  ourselves  with  productive  ability  in  a  sphere  in  which 
we  do  not  possess  even  receptive  capacity.  The  true  culture 
of  a  man  for  his  position  as  a  member  of  an  organism  requires 
two  things,  first,  personal  education,  and  then  also  the  cultiva- 
tion of  receptivity,  of  a  feeling  for  and  appreciation  of  others. 
Hence  it  is  a  capacity  for  transferring  oneself  to  the  stand- 
point of  others,  for  entering  into  their  special  cases  ("  I  am 
made  all  things  to  all  men,"  1  Cor.  ix.  22  ;  Acts  xv.  4),  a 
quality  which  is  the  prerequisite  of  all  influence  upon  others, 
all  mutual  giving  and  receiving.  The  memory  and  imagina- 
tion must  also  have  their  especial  share  in  this  education 
(cf.  Nitz.-ich's  sermon,  Die  Hciligung  dcr  Phantasic),  nor  must 
the  culture  of  sentiment  be  omitted.  This  in  its  ethic  form 
is  feeling,  its  opposite  is  insipidity  and  affectation.  The  over- 
culture  of  the  imagination  induces  to  luxuriating  in  mere 
diversion,  to  a  preponderance  of  a;stheticism,  to  that  intel- 
lectualism  which  is  now  a  tolerably  cheap  quality,  and  very 
different  from  intelligence  (Geist).  It  is  a  quality  readily 
combined  with  vanity,  affectation,  and  mannerism,  and,  more- 
over, with  extravagance  and  over-sensitiveness.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  non-cultivation  of  the  imagination  makes  a  man 
both  prosaic  and  pedantic.  Its  culture  is  of  great  importance 
to  piety,  which  needs  the  power  of  a  lively  conception  of  God 
and  of  Christ,  that  it  may  surrender  itself  thereto.  And  such 
co-operation  of  the  imagination  is,  so  far  as  it  is  necessary, 
not  untrue,  but  is  in  pre-established  harmony  with  the  truth, 
with  God  and  Christ. 

2.  Virtuous  stability.  It  might  be  thought  that  this  was 
a  gift,  and  not  to  be  required  of  all.  But  when  any 
one  gives  us  the  impression  of  having  a  light  and  shallow 
character,  when  our  intercourse  with  him  gives  us  the  feeling 
that  there  is  a  lack  of  mental  stamina  in  him,  we  do  not 
regard  this  as  entirely  the  fault  of  nature.  On  the  contrary, 
highly  gifted  and  ingenious  men  may  also  leave  this  impression 
and  the  dislike  connected  with  it,  which  destroys  confidence, 
and  consequently  cordiality.     What,  then,  do   we   mean  by 


484  §  65.    SELF-ASSEKTION  AND  SELF-MANIFESTATION. 

stability  ?  It  is  that  quality  in  a  man  wliicli  creates  the 
impression  that  he  is  constantly,  and  not  only  momentarily, 
influenced  by  his  moral  will,  i.e.  by  his  conscience,  or,  to 
speak  more  strictly,  by  the  thought  of  God,  and  therefore 
possesses  self-control.  To  such  a  man  we  involuntarily  accord 
our  confidence,  however  small  his  gifts,  or  however  limited 
his  sphere  of  operation.  If  we  are  but  certain  that  any  one 
submits  to  the  decision  of  conscience,  or  indeed  of  Christian 
piety,  we  know  also  that  he  is  not  shallow,  that  there  is  in 
him  depth  and  trustworthiness,  that  under  every  variety  of 
endowment  and  function  such  an  one  will  ever  be  at  unity 
with  himself,  and  therefore  neither  untruthful,  vacillating,  nor 
capricious,  but  simple  airXom,  a  sharer  in  the  Divine  unchange- 
ableness.  Thus  the  inward  multiplicity  is  collected  into  the 
focus  of  simplicity,  is  concentrated  in  singleness  of  moral  aim 
and  effort,  is  devoted  to  communion  with  God  and  the 
kingdom  of  God.  Not  till  this  concentration  takes  place  is  it 
possible  that  all  his  powers  and  gifts  should  undergo  the 
process  of  penetration,  and  every  single  virtue  come  into  the 
service  of  all  his  gifts — an  ethic  Treptp^wpTyat?.  Not  till  then 
is  he  a  complete  whole,  6\6ic\7]po<i,  an  aviip  reXeio^;  (Matt.  v. 
48,  vi.  22  ;  Jas.  i.  4,  6). 

Having  now  considered  Christian  self-love  with  respect  to 
one's  own  bodily  and  mental  state,  we  proceed  to  contemplate 
it  with  reference  to  others. 

II.    CHRISTIAN  SELF-LOVE  AS  SELF-ASSERTION  AND  SELF- 
MANIFESTATION  WITH  EEFERENGE  TO  OTHERS. 

§  65. 

The  negative  agency  by  which  personal  dignity  is  outwardly 
preserved  and  promoted,  is  Christian  endeavour  after  in- 
de-pendence  and  respect.  Its  inward  limits  are  humility 
and  love,  which  exclude  unrestrained  love  of  freedom, — 
avofiia,  —  and  ambition  no  less  than  servility.  The 
positive  agency  by  which  personal  dignity  and  due 
personal  influence  are  promoted,  is  self  -  manifestation. 
Its  animating  principle  or  impulse  is  communicative 
love,  in  alliance  with  the  negative  condition  of  truthful- 


CimiSTIAN  ENDEAVOUK  AFTER  INDEPENDENCE.  485 

ness,  which  requires  that  we  should  manifest  what  we 
really  are,  and  not  a  mere  semblance  of  ourselves.  In 
self-manifestation,  truthfulness  and  love  must  never  be 
separated,  and  thus  while  all  lies,  even  so-called  "  white 
lies,"  are  excluded,  it  must  always  have  the  good  as  its 
object.  Christian  wisdom  so  directs  self-manifestation 
on  the  impulse  of  love,  that  it  is  always  united  with 
truthfulness.  In  particular  is  self-manifestation  exhibited 
in  tlie  choice  of  a  vocation,  which  occupies  the  same  place 
in  the  intellectual  and  social  spheres,  that  property  does 
in  the  physical.      This  conducts  us  into  the  social  sphere. 

1.  Christian  endeavour  after  independence  has  respect  to  («) 
the  mind,  and  is  thus  opposed  to  servility  (Jas.  ii.  3)  ;  it  is 
an  assertion  of  personal  dignity,  and  is  also  opposed  to  the 
fear  of  man  and  to  men-pleasing — in  fact,  to  every  species 
of  idolatry  that  is  paid  to  persons  or  things  in  matters 
intellectual  or  spiritual.  It  includes  whatever  places  us  in 
false  dependence  upon  others — e.g.  entering  into  secret  associa- 
tions or  factions,  a  thing  which  is  especially  ruinous  in 
Church  life.  For  through  party  interests  of  a  factious  kind 
we  are  brought  into  a  position  where,  for  the  sake  of  obtaining 
success,  we  support  impure  measures  or  men,  or  become  their 
advocates,  and  carry  about  with  us  two  standards  of  judgment, 
one  to  be  used  when  we  are  among  our  party-associates, 
the  other  among  other  men  (1  Cor,  i.-iv.).  (h)  Christian 
endeavour  after  independence  has  respect  also  to  the  tody,  for 
as  long  as  a  man  is  not  master  of  his  own  body,  he  cannot 
manifest  his  personality  freely — e.g.  he  cannot  choose  his 
vocation.  Accordingly  the  New  Testament,  though  it  does 
not  directly  forbid  or  abolish  slavery,  yet  purposes  its  abolition 
in  a  moral  way  that  respects  the  rights  of  property.  "  If 
thou  canst  become  free,  use  it  rather"  (1  Cor.  vii.  21  f . ; 
Philem.  12  f.).  Christianity  does  not  indeed  allow  a  slave, 
who  is  lawful  property,  to  tahe  his  freedom.  In  slave  States, 
the  working  power  of  a  slave  has  become  of  money  value,  and 
comes  under  private  right.  Help  must  be  derived  not  from 
upsetting  the  rights  of  property,  but  from  a  recognition  of 
them,  though  after    a  Christian   manner   (§   63).      Thus,   for 


486  §  G5.    SELF-ASSERTION  AND  SELF-MANIFESTATION. 

example,  the  redemption  of  the  slaves  in  the  English  colonies 
by  the  State  was  a  magnificent  Christian  sacrifice  on  the  part 
of  the  State,  an  imitation  of  ancient  Christianity  when  it 
ransomed  Christian  slaves.  In  North  America,  too,  slavery 
has  of  late  been  legally  abolished.  But  at  present  the 
important  thing  is  to  afford  a  possibility  of  independence  to 
those  who  are  slaves,  and  this  the  Emperor  of  Paissia,  for 
example,  has  attempted  to  do  for  the  serfs.  For  this  purpose, 
however,  it  is  necessary  that  the  moral  sense  of  the  com- 
munity should  be  raised,  and  that  public  opinion  should 
advance  to  a  higher  conception  of  the  worth  of  the  Christian 
personality  ;  and  here  again  it  is  Christianity  that  can  render 
the  best  service.  Thus  Wilberforce,  Buxton,  and  their  friends, 
together  with  the  Quakers  and  Baptists,  prepared  public 
opinion  in  England  for  the  emancipation  of  the  slaves.  When 
once  the  Christian  idea  of  personality  has  attained  universal 
validity,  the  conviction  will  not  be  wanting  that  it  is  a  sin 
to  treat  a  man  as  a  mere  thing,  that,  on  the  contrary,  his 
dignity  as  Christ's  free  man  must  be  recognised,  and  efforts 
will  be  made  to  supply  the  slave  with  education,  and  in  parti- 
cular to  bestow  upon  him  the  blessing  of  Christianity.  It  is 
a  process  of  this  kind  which,  working  from  within  outwards, 
has  led  to  the  abolition  of  slavery  and  serfdom  in  European 
Christendom.  On  the  other  side,  when  the  Christian  idea  of 
personality  has  been  aroused  among  heathen  slaves  by  means 
of  missions,  it  does  not  follow  that  they  have  received  the 
signal  to  burst  their  chains.  But  the  power  of  Christianity 
shows  itself  conspicuously  in  this — that  even  in  such  unfavour- 
able circumstances  it  knows  how  to  rescue  the  personal 
dignity  of  the  slave,  and  to  make  him  independent  of  his  lot. 
The  slave,  who  has  become  a  Christian,  is  no  longer  inwardly 
a  mere  thing,  although  outwardly  he  is  so  still.  Inwardly  he 
is  the  Lord's  free  man,  and  has  to  show  his  thankfulness  for 
being  so  by  consoling  himself  with  this  inward  freedom 
which  is  the  chief  good,  when  he  cannot  alter  his  lot  without 
sin  and  rebellion  (Eph.  vi.  5-8;  Col.  iii.  11,  22  f . ;  1  Pet. 
ii.  16,  18  ;  Philem.  16).  And  in  so  doing  he  has,  in  truth,  a 
greater  share  of  freedom  than  his  master,  who,  ignorant  of 
higher  things,  is  a  slave  of  sin.  "With  regard  to  political 
freedom  also,  a  verdict  similar  to  the  above  must  be  passed, 


CARE  FOR  A  GOOD  NAME.  487 

or  even  a  still  stricter  oue.  Christianity,  and  especially 
Protestantism,  is  not  directly,  but  only  indirectly,  a  political 
principle.  Onr  filial  relationship  to  God  makes  us  all 
essentially  equal  with  respect  to  the  highest,  the  eternal 
sphere ;  and  by  virtue  of  this  supreme  good  we  can  patiently 
dispense  with  anything  that  is  still  wanting  to  our  comfort. 
It  would  be  sinful  for  the  Christian  to  regard  political  rights 
not  as  a  secondary,  Ijut  as  an  absolute  good,  or  to  try  to  secure 
them  by  a  breach  of  right,  and  thus  to  strive  after  a  merely 
relative  good  at  the  cost  of  doing  injury  to  one  that  is  absolute.^ 
2.  Care  for  our  Good  Name.  Importance  is  attached  to  a 
good  name  (Ps.  xli.  6  ;  Prov.  xxii.  1  ;  Eom.  xiii.  7 ;  1  Pet. 
ii.  17).  It  is  a  good  of  great  value,  a  condition  of  influence 
in  society.  But  our  Christian  care  for  our  good  name  must 
find  its  standard  in  humility  as  opposed  to  ambition,  as  well 
as  in  Christian  independence  of  the  world  and  of  what  the 
world  means  by  a  good  name  (against  the  passion  for  rank 
and  titles,  see  Matt,  xxiii.  7  ;  John  v.  41,  44,  xii.  43).  The 
way  of  duty  leads  not  merely  through  good,  but  also  through 
evil  report,  especially  as  the  judgment  of  the  multitude  is  so 
changeable  and  capricious  (2  Cor.  vi.  8  ;  Luke  vi.  26).  This 
care  for  our  good  name,  moreover,  does  not  consist  in  a  merely 
negative  warding  off  of  whatever  is  hurtful,  it  is  not  mere 
freedom  from  vice  and  crime  ;  it  demands  in  addition  to  this 
that  the  Christian  should  be  something  positively  good,  and 
make  it  manifest  that  he  is  so.  In  this  way  he  becomes  an 
authority  in  his  own  sphere ;  and  since  no  one  can  avoid 
acknowledging  spiritual  worth  and  pre-eminence,  he  thus 
acquires  a  position  of  influence.  But  such  acknowledgment 
cannot  be  compelled,  it  must  be  merited. 

§  66.    Continuation. 
TriUhfalness. 

The  Literature.— Krause,  Ueher  die  Wahrhaftigheit,  1844. 
Eeinhard,  iii.  pp.  163  f.,  195  f.,  199  f.      ISTitzsch,  System    der 

^  [Here  the  author  evidently  opposes  secondary  political  goods,  such  as 
political  liberty,  to  what  the  State  is  in  its  essential  nature.  The  idea  of  right, 
which  it  protects,  makes  the  State  an  object  of  worth  in  itself,  and  the  latter 
therefore  must  not  be  subverted  for  the  sake  of  merely  secondary  political  goods. 
In  addition,  of.  what  is  said  farther  on,  concerning  political  liberty,  in  the 
chapter  on  the  State. — Ed.] 


488  §  6G.    COI^TINUATIOX, 

Chrktlichen  Lchre,  4th  ed.  p.  312  f.,  §  172.  Harless,  Christian 
Ethik,  p.  295  sqq.  De  Wette,  Sittenlehrc,  iii.  126  f.  Eothe, 
1st  ed.  iii.  §  1073-1075.  Martenseu,  Christian  Ethics  (Clark's 
Translation,  i.  205-236). 

1.  Truthfulness  is  repeatedly  and  urgently  recommended  in 
the  New  Testament  (Matt.  v.  37  ;  Jas.  v.  12  ;  John  viii.  44  ; 
Eph.  iv.  21-25  ;  Col.  iii.  9  ;  1  Tim.  i.  10).  We  are  members 
one  of  another.  No  rational  being  makes  one  member  of  his 
body  deceive  another.  The  manifestation  of  the  Christian 
personality  with  regard  to  others  has  truthfulness  (which  is, 
besides,  a  duty  to  oneself)  as  its  negative,  and  love  as  its 
positive  characteristic  ;  while  both  in  contents  and  in  form 
it  is  determined  by  wisdom.  Truthfulness  is  of  a  negative 
character,  and  hence  it  does  not  form  a  complete  act  by  itself, 
it  is  only  a  moment  in  an  act.  Truth  does  not  demand  that 
all  that  is  in  a  man  should  be  brought  out ;  else  it  would  be 
a  moral  duty  for  him  to  let  also  the  evil  that  is  in  him  come 
forth,  whereas  it  is  his  duty  to  keep  it  down.  Truthfulness, 
therefore,  can  never  be  the  impulsive  power  in  self-manifesta- 
tion, it  is  love  alone  that  can  be  this,  unless  we  except  cases 
where  to  abstain  from  self-manifestation  would  amount  to 
positive  denial,  as  in  the  statiis  confessionis  (although  here, 
too,  love  to  Christ  is  ever  the  motive).  After  what  has  now 
been  said,  it  is  not  difficult  to  come  to  a  decision  respecting 
untruths,  falsehoods,  and  white  lies.  An  untruth  considered 
in  itself  is  something  of  a  wholly  objective  kind,  and  does  not 
necessarily  imply  nntruthfulness.  It  takes  place  whenever 
something  else  than  the  objective  truth — perhaps  its  very 
opposite — is  set  forth,  and  error  thus  produced  in  the  minds 
of  others.  But  at  the  same  time  the  speaker  may  be  himself 
in  error,  and  consequently  subjective  truthfulness  maintained. 
On  the  other  hand,  untruthfulness — that  is,  subjective  un- 
truth or  falsehood  —  takes  place  when  the  speaker  speaks 
against  his  own  conviction,  even  should  vjhat  he  says  he  true. 
If  along  witli  this  he  intends  to  deceive,  then  his  lie  acquires 
also  a  social  aspect  that  is  hostile  to  love.  And  here  actions 
are  included  as  well  as  words.  The  use  of  rouge,  e.g.,  involves 
the  intention  of  making  others  l^elieve  that  there  is  mor« 
beauty  or  youth  beneath  it,  than  is  actually  the  case.  On  the 
other  liand,  where  the  artificial  means  employed  have  created 


TRUTHFULNESS,  489 

a  false  appearance,  but  at  the  same  time  this  is  not  the 
intention  of  the  act,  then  there  is  no  falsehood.  The  pur- 
pose, e.g.,  may  be  to  cover  a  bodily  blemish,  or  to  conceal  some 
repulsive  natural  defect,  or  for  health's  sake  to  seek  an 
artificial  compensation  for  something  that  has  been  lost. 
Here  there  is  no  falsehood,  for  it  is  not  a  duty  to  expose  what 
is  offensive,  or  to  endure  it,  when  the  power  we  have  over 
nature  enables  us  to  supply  the  deficiency.  ISTevertheless,  if 
the  means  that  may  be  used  to  cover  a  defect  are  changed 
into  a  means  for  making  a  dazzling  display  of  beauty,  then 
falsehood  arises.  The  case  is  somewhat  different  with  regard 
to  our  conventional  phrases  of  politeness.^  These  certainly 
contain  many  false  exaggerations,  that  have  arisen  from  the 
effort  to  talk  in  a  complimentary  fashion,  or  from  people 
trying  to  attain  some  end  by  means  of  flattery.  The  Quakers 
are  wholly  averse  to  such  forms  of  speech,  and  have  broken 
with  them,  and  we  can  accept  their  attitude  in  the  matter  as 
a  Christian  protest  against  the  continuance  of  tliese  habits  and 
forms.  Still  we  must  not  characterize  such  customary  modes 
of  expression  as  lies,  since  they  resemble  worn-out  coins, 
which  in  the  course  of  exchange  have  acquired  a  different 
value  from  what  their  inscriptions  denote.  If  an  individual 
were  to  attempt  to  alter  these  forms,  he  would  occasion 
another  false  impression — namely,  the  appearance  of  inten- 
tional impoliteness  or  insult.  The  Quakers  run  no  risk  of 
doing  so,  because  every  one  knows  that,  in  refusing  to  use 
these  forms  of  speech,  they  have  no  intention  whatever  of 
giving  offence.  But  Quakers  also  go  too  far  with  their 
universal  use  of  "  Thou ; "  for  it  is  important  to  human 
society  that  politeness,  too,  should  have  a  sphere  of  its  own 
where  courtesy  and  deference  alone  are  manifested,  a  sphere 
half-way  between  non-acquaintance  and  intimacy.  This  is  the 
outer  court  of  the  temple  of  social  intercourse,  and  we  may 
not  enter  in  by  any  other  way.  Men  must  still  continue  tu 
respect  each  other,  though  they  are  not  on  a  footing  of  intimacy. 
2.  But  now  are  there  cases  where  lying  is  alloicahle  ?  Can 
we  make  out  the  so-called  white  lie  to  be  morally  permissible  ? 
The  insane,  the  sick,  children  are  involved,  in  manifold  ways, 
in  false  ideas,  in  a  world  of  appearances.  Is  it  right  for  us  to 
^  Of.  Schleiermacher,  Christlkhe  SUte,  p.  654  f. 


490  §  G(3.    CONTINUATION. 

accommodate  ourselves  to  them  out  of  love  ?  To  let  them 
remain  amid  appearances  when  to  dissipate  these  would  be 
precipitate,  to  withhold  the  truth  from  them  when  it  would 
not  benefit  them,  and  they  would  form  a  false  conception  of  it, 
— this  is  permissible  beyond  doubt ;  for  all  moral  communica- 
tions have  love,  not  truthfulness,  as  their  impulse  (John 
xvi.  12  ;  Matt.  vii.  6)  (Kvve^).  But  is  it  also  allowable  to 
carry  accommodation  so  far  as  to  give  assent  to  errors,  even 
should  it  be  with  the  purpose  of  afterwards  overcoming  them, 
when  we  have  thus  won  confidence  ?  Or,  what  comes  to  the 
same  thing,  is  it  allowable  to  cixate  a  false  appearance  {fucum)  ? 
In  general,  and  in  accordance  with  what  has  already  been 
said,  it  must  hold  good,  that  whoever  regards  something  that 
is  really  a  lie — a  so-called  white  lie — as  permissible,  must 
also  look  upon  it  as  a  duty.  But  how  shall  ethics  ever  be 
brought  to  lay  down  a  duty  of  lying,  to  recommend  evil  that 
good  may  come  ?  (Eom.  iii.  8).  The  test  for  us  is,  whether 
we  could  ever  imagine  Christ  acting  in  this  way,  either  for  the 
sake  of  others,  or — which  would  be  quite  as  justifiable,  since 
self-love  is  a  moral  duty — for  His  otvn  sake.  To  accom- 
modate ourselves  to  oilier^— e.g.  to  children  or  those  who  are 
sick — is  no  doubt  a  duty,  but  it  must  have  its  limits ;  and 
these  are  given  in  saying  that  we  must  not  contradict  our- 
selves— that  is  to  say,  there  must  be  no  contradiction  between 
our  inward  mind  or  opinion  and  our  outward  words  or  acts. 
In  particular,  to  withhold  the  truth  from  one  who  is  dying,  to 
give  him  false  hopes  when  all  hope  is  gone,  is  questionable  for 
this  reason — that  we  thereby  take  something  from  him,  the 
incentive,  namely,  to  prepare  himself  for  death  both  outwardly 
and  inwardly,  that  he  may  take  the  last  step,  the  step  from 
life  to  death,  consciously  and  willingly.  We  overestimate 
the  value  of  human  life,  and  besides  we  in  a  measure  usurp 
the  place  of  Providence,  when  we  believe  we  may  save  it  by 
committing  sin.  There  are  certainly  cases,  however,  where 
the  ai^pcarance  produced  is  -quite  honed,  where  the  untruth  is 
confessedly  an  untruth,  and  is  by  this  means  preserved  from 
being  immoral.  Thus  playful  fictions  may  be  propounded  by 
friends  amongst  each  other,  after  the  manner  of  riddles,  in 
which,  by  way  of  free  mental  diversion,  they  have  to  guess 
what  they  are  to  think  of  them.     In  war,  too,  something  like  a 


DEGREE  OF  GUILT  IN  LIES.  491 

game  of  this  kind  is  carried  on,  when  by  way  of  stratagem 
some  deceptive  appearance  is  produced,  and  a  riddle  is  thus 
given  to  the  enemy.  In  such  cases  there  is  no  falsehood  ;  for, 
from  the  conditions  of  the  situation, — whether  friendly  or 
hostile, — the  appearance  that  is  given  is  confessedly  nothing 
more  than  an  appearance,  and  is  therefore  honest.  On  the 
other  hand,  I  should  be  unwilling  to  extend  what  has  just 
been  said  to  the  social  phrase  in  which  a  person  denies  him- 
self to  visitors.  Unless,  perhaps,  it  has  become  conventional 
to  understand  the  formula  "  not  at  home  "  as  meaning  "  I  am 
prevented  from  receiving,  lait  wish  you  to  regard  my  refusal 
not  as  if  I  had  repulsed  you,  but  as  if  you  liad  missed  me  " 
(as  against  Rothe). 

3.  With  regard,  however,  to  the  degree  of  guilt  attaching  to 
lies,  of  necessity  a  distinction  must  certainly  be  made.  If  the 
lie  is  selfish,  as  so-called  white  lies  generally  are,  it  is  simply 
dishonourable,  and  a  fraud  ;  and  whoever  as  a  matter  of  prin- 
ciple allows  himself  to  tell  such  lies  for  his  own  advantage, 
shows  that  his  sense  of  truthfulness  is  fundamentally  im- 
paired. But  the  amount  of  guilt  must  be  otherwise  estimated, 
if  the  lie  was  told  in  the  interests  of  love,  and  in  defence  of  a 
good  legitimate  in  itself.  In  such  a  case,  however,  there  must 
be  no  indifference  to  the  preservation  of  truthfulness,  for  then 
the  love  that  is  displayed  would  probably  be  altogether  super- 
ficial. But  an  act  may  amount  to  a  lie  even  when  it  was 
originally  intended  to  be  pure,  and  to  preserve  not  only  love 
but  also  truthfulness  uninjured.  We  may  intend,  e.g.,  not  to 
tell  a  lie,  but  only  to  maintain  a  conscientious  silence,  and  yet 
in  carrying  out  our  intention  fail  to  fulfil  the  duty  of  keeping- 
truth  and  love  united.  Here  the  will  was  good,  but  from 
want  of  moral  skill  or  wisdom  our  act  has  so  fallen  out  that 
silence  has  become  deception.  This  is  again  a  case  that  puts 
to  the  proof  our  moral  advancement,  and  its  solution  therefore 
depends  upon  the  degree  of  discretion  and  prudence  we  have 
attained  (Matt.  x.  16).  The  impulse  to  act  must  always 
come  from  love ;  truthfulness  is  only  the  negative  side  of 
action,  except  in  the  status  confcssionis  (§  55).  Consequently, 
whenever  revealing  the  truth  is  opposed  to  love,  it  would 
show  want  of  love  to  communicate  it.  Now,  should  a  case 
arise  where  an  act  is  not  intended  to  deceive,  but  truthfulness 


492  §  07.    CONTINUATION. 

is  meant  to  be  preserved,  and  should  the  result  be  that,  in 
guarding  the  interests  of  love,  we  do  injury  to  truthfulness, 
then  it  must  be  said  that,  relatively  speaking,  it  was  better 
that  the  chief  moral  requisite  of  the  situation — viz.  love — 
should  not  suffer  loss.  Still  the  act  itself,  though  perhaps, 
with  the  degree  of  moral  strength  existing,  unavoidable,  must 
be  to  the  Christian  an  object  of  regret  and  repentance, — and 
that  not  merely  on  its  own  account,  but  because  of  the  state  of 
character  to  which  the  fault  was  due. 

§  67.   Continuation. 

Oaths. 

In  an  oath  we  solemnly,  and  in  spoken  words,  connect  a 
statement  with  the  thought  of  God  as  the  Omniscient 
Witness  and  Eighteous  Judge  of  untruth.  Where  it  is 
found  to  be  necessary,  it  points  to  a  sinful  condition  of 
society,  and  is  accordingly  destined  to  cease  along  with 
the  evils  which  occasion  it.  But  in  itself  an  oath  is  not 
a  sin  ;  on  the  contrary,  when  the  truth  cannot  in  im- 
portant matters  be  otherwise  established,  it  is  our  duty 
both  to  put  a  person  on  his  oath  and  to  give  our  own. 

Literature.  —  Stiiudlin,  Gcschichtc  dcr  Vorstellungcn  unci 
Lehrcn  vom  Eid,  1824.  Bayer,  Betrachtimgen  ilher  den  Uid, 
1829.  Bauer,  Ueber  den  Eid,  moralisch-thcologischer  Versuch. 
Nitzsch,  Predigt  uber  die  Heiligkeit  des  Eides.  Goschl,  Der 
Eid  nach  seinem  Prinzipe,  Begriffe  und  Gehrauche,  18.37. 
Sti-ippelmann,  Der  Gerichtseid,  1855.  Eothe,  1st  ed.  iii. 
§  1076. 

1.  Its  Idea.  The  various  kinds  of  oaths  make  no  essential 
difference  to  the  idea  of  an  oath.  A  distinction  is  made 
between  («)  civil  oaths  (word  of  honour)  and  (h)  religious  oaths. 
Both  of  these  classes,  again,  are  divided  into  judicial  and 
imvatc  oaths.  According  to  their  occasion  or  their  contents, 
oaths  are  partly  those  of  conviction  (jarcmienta-  credulitatis), 
where  a  subjective  conviction  concerning  some  matter  is 
stated  on  oath  (as  in  the  case  of  a  jury,  for  instance),  and 
partly  corrohorative.  The  latter  are  either  negative — oaths  of 
2)urgation  {juramcnta  piirgationis),  for  the  purpose  of  rebutting 


OATHS.  493 

an  assertion — or  positive — assertory  oaths  (juramcnta  assertoria). 
Among  the  latter  are  oaths  connected  with  the  giving  of 
evidence  and  with  promises,  the  oath  of  citizenship,  of  office, 
and  of  allegiance,  as  well  as  cases  where  a  confession  of  faith 
is  accompanied  with  an  oath  and  a  vow  or  promise,  as,  for 
example,  in  the  so-called  religious  oath.  An  oath  has  been 
regarded  under  the  aspect  both  (a)  of  a  covenant,  and  (6)  of  a 
confession;  the  former  chiefly  in  the  last  century. 

(a)  The  oath  as  a  covenant ;  (a)  loith  God.  In  an  oath,  it 
is  said,  the  highest  goods  are  put  in  pledge.  To  include  God 
Himself  among  these  goods  would  give  no  sense,  and  therefore 
it  must  be  eternal  blessedness  that  is  meant.  But  such  a 
relationship  with  regard  to  God  as  a  contract  implies,  would 
be  immoral  in  itself;  it  would  be  opposed  to  humility.  And 
then,  how  can  it  be  right  for  a  man  to  pledge  salvation  for 
any  earthly  thing  whatever  ?  Further,  however  certain  a 
statement  may  be  to  which  we  give  our  oath,  it  ought  not  to 
be  as  certain  to  ns  as  God  and  the  blessedness  we  have  in 
fellowship  with  Him.  How,  therefore,  can  a  true  Christian,  to 
whom  God  is  more  certain  than  the  empirical  world,  nay,  who 
has  derived  true  assurance  from  God  alone — how  can  he  ever 
say  with  truth,  that  any  earthly  thing  whatever  is  as  certain 
to  him  as  God  and  fellowship  with  God  ?  With  those,  how- 
ever, to  whom  not  God  and  salvation,  but  something  that  is 
earthly,  is  the  highest  good  or  the  clearest  certainty,  an  oath 
in  this  conception  of  it  would  afford  no  guarantee  of  truth. 
And  thus  it  follows  that  pious  Christians  could  not  take  an 
oath  in  this  sense  of  the  M'ord,  and  that  those  who  do  take  it 
would  not  be  pious. 

(/3)  Michaelis  represents  an  oath  as  a  contract  between  the 
person  who  gives  it  and  the  person  to  whom  it  is  given 
(acljurans).  Here  God  is  the  fjuarantee  of  the  contract.  But 
this  would  look  as  if  a  special  contract  were  necessary  in 
order  to  make  truthfulness  obligatory,  and  as  if  God  were  not 
the  judge  of  all  untruth.  This  conception,  therefore,  tends  to 
moral  laxity  with  reference  to  declarations  not  made  upon 
oath. 

(7)  Instead  of  this  juridical  conception  of  an  oath,  we  have 
the  moral  conception,  as  in  the  civil  oath,  where  one's  word  of 
honour  is    passed,   or   moral   honour   is   pledged.     Even    an 


494  §  G7.    CONTINUATION. 

atheist  could  take  an  oath  of  this  kind.  But  while  moral 
honour  is  no  doubt  rightly  comprehended  in  an  oath,  it 
includes  religious  honour,  and  the  latter  must  be  made  promi- 
nent in  an  oath,  because  it  alone  affords  security  that  the  person 
who  takes  the  oath  occupies  a  fundamentally  moral  position. 

(h)  Consequently,  Goschel's  conception  is  more  to  be  com- 
mended, according  to  which  an  oath  is  a  religious  confession, 
an  act  of  worship.  Still,  it  is  again  incorrect  to  regard  this 
as  exhausting  the  meaning  of  an  oath,  for  in  that  case  it 
would  be  a  wholly  desirable  act,  and  no  disapproval  could 
attach  to  it  (in  opposition  to  Matt.  v.).  This  would  mean  that 
an  individual  is  here  performing  a  religious  act,  an  act  of 
worship,  in  the  presence  of  his  fellow-men,  in  order  to  assure 
them  that  he  is  a  religious  man.  But,  while  one  of  the 
results  of  an  oath  may  very  well  be  to  convince  iis  that  we 
are  dealing  with  a  religiously  conscientious  man,  still  this 
must  not  be  the  purpose  of  him  who  takes  it ;  for  then  the 
act  of  worship  would  be  performed,  not  for  its  own  sake,  but 
in  a  manner  to  suggest  display.  On  the  contrary,  since  the 
statement  that  is  to  be  attested  refers  to  a  single  finite  fact, 
which  may  be  altogether  separated  from  the  thought  of  God, 
while  at  the  same  time  it  is  necessary  to  arrive  at  certainty 
concerning  this  fact,  the  essential  nature  of  an  oath  consists  in 
this — that  he  who  makes  it  brings  his  statement  into  connection 
with  the  thouglit  of  God,  and  makes  confession  that  he  is 
speaking  hcforc  God  in  all  good  conscicjice. 

2.  NeiD  Testament  passages  witli  regard  to  an  oath  are 
Matt.  V.  33  ff.,  xxiii.  16-22;  Jas.  v.  12.  Here  swearing  is 
forbidden  oXw?.  Some  hold  that  it  is  only  an  oath  attached 
to  a  promise  which  is  forbidden,  because  we  are  not  nostri 
juris  (Grotius).  But  the  command  is — Swear  not  at  all 
(oXw?).  Others  maintain  that  it  is  only  extrajudicial  oaths 
which  are  forbidden.  But  no  grounds  can  be  shown  for 
excluding  these,  if  judicial  oaths  are  allowed,  because  we  may 
lie  brought  into  the  status  confcssionis  in  private,  as  well  as  in 
public  circumstances.  It  has  further  been  held  that  we  are 
only  forbidden  to  swear  by  finite  things,  such  as  the  temple, 
heaven,  or  earth,  etc.,  but  are  not  forbidden  to  swear  by  God ; 
the  reason  being  that  in  the  former  case  we  are  apt  to  be 
betrayed  into  thoughtlessness  in  the  matter  of  taking  an  oath. 


OATHS.  495 

But  what  Christ  says  is,  that  in  swearing  by  finite  things  we 
are  in  reality  swearing  by  God,  and  that  we  ought  not  to 
swear  at  alL  Hence  it  need  not  surprise  us  that  scrupulously 
conscientious  parties,  such  as  Quakers  and  Mennonites,  reject 
oath-taking  altogether.  And  there  is  much  to  countenance 
this  position.  An  oath  arises  from  sin,  it  is  sin  alone  whicli 
calls  for  it ;  for  it  can  only  be  necessary  when  society  is  much 
infected  with  the  vice  of  lying,  when  a  simple  yea,  yea,  nay, 
nay,  is  no  longer  sufficient,  and  statements  unsupported  by  an 
oath  are  exposed  to  suspicion.  Further,  where  oath-taking  is 
practised,  the  duty  of  telliyirj  the  truth  when  not  upon  our  oath 
seems  to  be  'put  lotoer  than  the  duty  of  telling  it  lohen  upon 
oath.  But  by  this  means  the  sense  of  duty  is  weakened  in 
the  sphere  of  ordinary  life,  the  truthftdness  of  a  people  is 
undermined,  oaths  become  more  and  more  common,  and  by 
reason  of  their  very  frequency  become  useless  and  even  per- 
nicious, since  tlieir  evidential  value  is  constantly  decreasing. 
This  injury,  which  may  be  inflicted  on  the  general  truthfulness 
of  a  people,  cannot  be  measured,  but  the  mischief  is  as  great 
as  if  oaths  were  to  be  discontinued,  and  many  single  facts 
were  to  remain  unproved,  especially  as  the  security  which  an 
oath  affords  is  so  often  merely  formal.  In  addition  to  all 
this,  the  honour  of  the  Christian  is  affected.  He  speaks  the 
truth  plainly  and  simply ;  to  demand  an  oath  from  him 
implies  mistrust  of  his  simple  assertion,  and  therefore,  if  he  is 
really  a  Christian,  his  honour  is  injured.  Ought  he  to  submit 
to  this  ?  Further,  among  those  parties  that  refuse  to  take  an 
oath,  there  by  no  means  seems  to  be  more  untruthfulness 
than  where  statements  are  made  upon  oath.  On  the  contrary, 
their  release  from  the  obligation  to  take  an  oath  is  for  them  a 
mark  of  distinction,  and  an  incentive  to  truthfulness,  while  at 
the  same  time  it  justifies  the  State  in  making  the  punishment 
of  any  abuse  of  confidence  all  the  more  severe,  and  hence  it 
may  be  doubtful  whether  a  community  would  not  be  better 
off  were  oaths  abolished  altogether,  and  the  precepts  of  the 
Xew  Testament  literally  followed. 

On  the  other  hand,  we  must  also  admit  that  Christ  Himself 
on  various  occasions  confirmed  His  words  with  an  "  Amen, 
amen ; "  and  that  when  the  High  Priest  adjured  Him  to  speak 
the  truth  upon  an   oath  which  he  proposed,  Jesus  replied, 


496  §  67.    CONTINUATION. 

"  Thou  liast  said,"  and  thus  consented  to  the  oath,  Matt. 
xxvi.  63.  Similarly  we  tind  Paul  also  frequently  making 
asseverations,  Eom.  i.  9,  ix.  1  ;  2  Cor.  xi.  31,  xii.  2  ;  1  Thess. 
ii.  5,  10;  2  Cor.  i.  23  ;  1  Tim.  v.  21.  In  Heb.  vi.  16,  an 
oath  is  called  the  end  of  all  strife.  Further,  in  the  Old  Testa- 
ment, oaths  are  spoken  of  as  acts  that  are  moral,  or  are  even 
legally  enjoined,  and  God  is  described  as  swearing  by  Himself, 
Ex.  xxii.  11;  Lev.  vi.  3;  Gen.  xxii.  16,  xxvi.  3;  Num. 
xiv.  21  ;  Ps.  Ixxxix.  4,  ex.  4  ;  Ezek.  xxxiii.  11  ;  Isa.  xlv.  23. 
In  fact,  it  cannot  he  shown  why  there  should  he  anything  turong 
in  an  oath,  if  the  truth  cannot  be  otherwise  made  credible ; 
for  if  it  is  sincerely  taken,  it  merely  bears  witness  to  the  fact 
that  God  is  remembered  in  connection  vi^ith  the  statement  that 
is  made.  But,  all  the  same,  the  thought  of  God  should  be 
continually  present  to  the  Christian,  so  that  an  oath  contains 
nothing  new  or  foreign,  but  only  something  that  is  good. 
We  cannot  compel  men  to  believe  our  simple  word ;  in  a 
court  of  justice  all  must  be  treated  alike ;  and  since  lying 
exists  in  our  social  life,  every  one  who  would  be  a  member 
of  society  must  assist  in  bearing  like  a  Christian  the  burden 
to  which  falsehood  gives  rise.  Moreover,  where  oaths  are 
administered,  it  does  not  necessarily  folloiu  that  statements  not 
made  ujwn  oath  have  their  value  Imvered,  or  that  the  spirit  of 
truthfulness  in  general  is  weakened.  Means  can  be  devised 
to  obviate  these  dangers  without  forbidding  oaths  entirely. 
But  at  the  same  time  we  must  always  endeavour  to  render 
oaths  less  and  less  frequent,  and  more  and  more  dispensable. 
If  only  the  objective  duty  of  truthfulness  is  enforced  with 
sufficient  earnestness,  a  community  will  be  none  the  worse  for 
oaths  being  permitted ;  they  will  serve  as  a  reminder  of  the 
duty  of  truthfulness  in  general.  Consequently,  the  sayings 
of  Christ  directed  against  oaths  must  be  understood  as  follows. 
Oaths  ought  to  be  strictly  excluded  as  between  Christians, 
because,  although  they  are  sincerely  taken,  they  are  neverthe- 
less superfluous.  Further,  the  principle  remains,  that  our 
object  should  be  to  make  oaths  dispensable,  and  bring  about 
their  entire  discontinuance.  Hence  they  are  rightly  employed 
only,  when  at  the  same  time  the  duty  of  truthfulness  in  general 
is  enforced  in  such  a  way  as  to  make  the  taking  of  oaths, 
itself  a  step  toivards  rendering  them  n/)  longer  necessary.     Christ 


OATHS.  497 

therefore  does  not  set  xip  a  mere  empty  ideal  or  aim,  but 
presents  truthfulness  throughout  the  whole  life  of  a  people  as 
the  real  aim  of  the  Christian.  Within  these  limits  an  oath 
can  receive  its  due  ethical  place,  as  something  that  is 
transitory,  as  the  expression  of  a  momentarily  imperfect 
condition  of  society,  but  the  expression,  too,  of  a  real  and 
ceaseless  striving  after  the  true  goal.  It  belongs  to  the 
freedom  of  the  Christian  to  take  upon  himself,  in  the  spirit 
of  love,  something  that  is  not  necessary  for  himself,  but  is 
occasioned  by  the  average  ethical  state  of  society.  From 
what  has  been  said,  however,  it  follows  that  an  increase  in  the 
frcqiLcncy  of  oaths  is  a  disgrace  to  a  Christian  commonwealth, 
a  sign,  if  not  of  levity,  yet  of  indolence  on  the  part  of  judges, 
and  of  the  decay  of  truthfulness  in  the  community  at  large. 

3.  An  oath  does  nothing  to  raise  the  objective  duty  of 
truthfulness  to  a  higher  level,  for  objectively  there  are  no 
differences  of  degree  between  duties.  But  subjectively,  and 
in  a  religious  way,  it  does  enhance  our  obligation  to  tell  tlie 
truth  ;  he  who  takes  it  must  either  say  what  is  true,  or  else 
grieve  the  Spirit  of  God,  who  is  warning  him  to  be  truthful, 
and  thus  become  a  worse  man  than  he  was  before.  The  guilt 
of  untruthfulness  is  thus  incalculably  increased  by  perjury. 
Accordingly,  (a)  an  oath  must  not  be  taken  without  well- 
tested  conviction.  (/S)  No  one  must  be  compelled,  or  allow 
himself  to  be  compelled,  to  take  an  oath ;  for  if  swearing  be 
altogether  contrary  to  a  man's  moral  sense,  then  if  he  did 
swear,  he  would  sin  against  himself.  (7)  Still  less  must  he 
who  administers  an  oath  allow  one  to  be  taken  for  statements, 
when  the  contrary  of  these  has  already  been  affirmed  upon 
oath.  (8)  Further,  since  an  oath  does  not  create  a  new  duty, 
but  only  makes  an  objective  duty  more  binding  subjectively, 
it  also  follows  that  just  as  nothing  impossible  must  be  pro- 
mised on  oath,  so,  too,  nothing  immoral  can  become  a  duty 
by  having  an  oath  attached  to  it.  But  we  must  certainly 
maintain,  that  if  the  oath  was  on  the  whole  permissible,  it 
ought  to  be  kept.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  it  was  immoral, 
then,  while  we  refuse  to  adhere  to  it,  we  ought  to  be  filled 
with  earnest  contrition  for  our  sin  in  entering  into  it,  and 
with  penitent  sorrow  for  the  offence  and  confusion  of  moral 
ideas  to  which  our  conduct  so  readily  gives  rise.     Finally,  we 

2  I 


498  §  68.    CONTINUATION. 

ought  also  to  be  willing  to  accept  all  the  injurious  conse- 
quences of  our  sin,  in  order  to  make  atonement  for  the  offence 
we  have  caused.  Hurtful  consequences  of  an  external  kind, 
injuries  that  follow  in  the  secondary  spheres,  and  the  like,  do 
not  release  us  from  an  oath ;  it  is  only  plain  immorality  that 
can  make  a  promise  null  and  void  in  itself.  He  who  would 
make  any  damage  he  might  sustain  in  consequence  of  keeping 
his  word  to  be  something  immoral,  shows  that  he  is  material- 
istic in  his  ideas,  and  unbelieving  with  regard  to  God's  bless- 
ing on  fidelity. 

§  68.  Continuation. 

Our  Vocation. 

There  is  also  and  essentially  an  individual  side  to  the  activity 
of  the  man  created  in  God's  image  (§13  ff'.).  Moreover, 
since,  though  he  is  endowed  with  individual  gifts,  his 
feeling  for  the  general  good  is  constantly  evidencing 
itself  in  a  moral  manner,  his  self-manifestation  and 
self-activity  are  carried  out  in  a  particular  vocation. 

1.  In  what  has  hitherto  been  said  in  treating  of  Christian 
character,  we  have  not  given  any  special  prominence  to  the 
individual  or  social  factors.  We  have  regarded  both  the 
physical  and  spiritual  duties  which  Christians  owe  to  them- 
selves more  under  this  aspect,  without  absolutely  defining  the 
individual  point  of  view.  Even  such  matters  as  truthfulness 
and  oaths  have  not  been  brought  'pvimo  loco  under  the  social 
or  individual  point  of  view,  but  under  that  of  Christian  honour 
and  its  self-assertion.  In  this  paragraph  we  turn  away  from 
the  personal  to  the  individual  side.  In  so  doing  we  seem  to 
be  farther  removed  than  ever  from  what  is  social,  while 
nevertheless  personal  honour  is  inseparably  connected  with  the 
moral  position  which  one  bears  to  others,  to  the  social  sphere 
at  large.  But,  in  truth,  it  is  just  the  individual  side  of  the 
Christian  personality,  which  forms  the  transition  to  objective 
communities,  and  conducts  us  from  the  subjective  to  the 
objective  form  in  which  the  highest  good  is  realized.  Tor 
moral  individuality  on  the  side  of  its  power  of  manifestation  is 


OUK  VOCATION.  499 

talent  (or  when  Christian,  'x^dpia/jia),  which  is  indispensable  to 
the  formation  and  self-preservation  of  an  organized,  moral 
world,  just  as  this  world  again  assigns  to  talent  its  place  or 
vocation  (1  Cor.  xii.  4  ff,  28  K,  xiv. ;  Matt  xxv.  15  ff.; 
Luke  xix.  13-25).  Every  individual  is  indeed  a  microcosm, 
reflecting  the  whole  of  existence,  both  God  and  the  world ; 
each  one,  however,  does  not  reflect  everything  in  the  same  way, 
but  in  a  different  way  from  every  one  else.  That  is  to  say, 
the  predominant  characteristic  is  different  in  each  individual, 
and  modifies  all  his  energies.  When  a  person  is  pre-eminently 
endowed  on  one  side  of  his  nature,  he  is  of  necessity  limited 
on  other  sides,  so  far  at  least  as  productive  power  is  con- 
cerned ;  and  it  is  only  within  its  proper  limits  that  his  special 
skill  can  be  exhibited.  They  are  for  us  the  negative  condition 
of  concentration.  At  the  same  time,  such  limitation  forms  a 
strong  social  ho7id,  rendering  it  necessary  for  the  accomplish- 
ment of  work  that  all  should  reciprocally  sujpylement  each 
other.  With  regard  to  our  inward  disposition,  however,  no 
such  process  of  supplementing  can  be  admitted,  because 
inwardly  each  one  ought  to  be  devoted  to  the  whole,  with  open 
heart  and  in  faithful  love.  If  there  were  only  identity, 
individuals  would,  on  the  other  hand,  remain  like  so  many 
atoms  alongside  of  each  other  in  their  action.  And  an  infinite 
repetition  of  one  and  the  same  would  never  make  an  organism. 
It  is  true  that  the  idea  of  God  is  reflected  in  its  totality  in 
every  single  person.  But  different  sides  of  this  idea  are 
reflected  individually  in  separate  individuals ;  these  become  so 
many  different  talents,  and  constitute  a  diversity  that  aims  at 
and  establishes  the  different  spheres  of  vocation  or  different 
communities,  in  which  is  realized  the  awiia  Xpiarou,  the 
kingdom  of  God, — that  greatest  and  holiest  of  all  works  of 
art,  that  splendid  temple  of  God,  that  is  luilt  not  of  stones,  hut 
of  persons.  And  although  persons  die,  yet  these  communities 
endure,  and  have  a  relative  immortality,  since  new  individuals 
are  constantly  arising  to  caoTy  on  those  essential  functions, 
through  which  every  community  is  loroducccl  and  organized. 
Attaching  himself,  with  his  individual  capacities,  to  these 
communities/    each    individual   is   now   raised,    and   has  his 

^  In  treating  of  the  genesis  of  vocations,  we  can  either  begin  with  individuals 
and  proceed  to  communities,  or  begin  with  tlie  communities  themselves  in  which 


500  §  68.    CONTINUATION. 

moral  life  raised,  to  a  higher  level ;  for  it  is  now  essential  to 
his  personal  honour,  as  belonging  to  a  particular  vocation,  that 
he  should  not  so  much  act  of  himself,  as  that  the  moral  spirit 
of  his  sphere  of  life  should  act  through  him.  Individuals, 
indeed,  remain  the  vehicles  of  virtues,  for  Vinet  is  right  in 
maintaining  that  the  moral  communities  are  not  possessors  of 
virtuousness.  Individuals,  however,  are  the  vehicles  of  the 
virtues  of  their  vocation  by  this  means  alone — that  they  do 
not  merely  think  and  act  as  individuals,  but  that  the  Ethos, 
the  spirit  of  the  whole  community  (which,  in  the  case  of 
Christians,  is  the  Holy  Spirit),  is  the  principle  which  impels 
and  animates  them,  whether  in  the  Church,  the  State,  in 
Science  or  in  Art.  The  physical  person  becomes  the  organ  of 
a  higher,  of  the  moral  person  or  community.  An  individual 
has  not  truly  found  himself,  until  he  has  found  his  moral 
vocation,  which  makes  him  a  useful  organ,  animated  by  the 
consciousness  and  will  of  the  whole  community. 

2.  Vocation ;  its  Universality.  Since  the  gift  possessed  by 
each  Christian  is  held  by  him  for  the  common  good  (1  Cor.  xiv. 
12,  26),  it  naturally  follows  that  Christian  society  ought  not 
to  have  any  drones  who  merely  consume,  and  do  nothing  to 
nourish  it.  Every  man  must  have  a  vocation,  a  special  one, 
not  merely  the  fundamental  or  family  vocation,  arising  from 
his  position  in  the  family,  which  is  the  basis  of  all  other 
moral  communities.  It  is  woman  alone  who  has  the  latter  as 
her  proper  vocation,^  and  hence  she  is  also  the  vehicle  of  the 
universal  human.  But  every  man  must  have  a  special 
vocation  besides  the  family  one.  "  The  man  must  not  be  a 
stay-at-home"  (Rothe).  Marheinecke^  and  Rothe^  I'ightly 
declaim  against  private  gentlemen  and  squires,  who  make 
such  a  figure  in  the  "  Visitors'  List "  at  watering-places,  and 
are  not  producers,  but  only  consumers ;  and  with  striking 
force  compare  them  to  beggars,  the  parasites  of  society.  If 
any  will  not  work,  neither  let  him  eat  (2  Thess.  iii.  10-12). 
When  men  have  no  longer  the  strength  to  carry  on  their 
own   calling,  civic  duties  and  church  work  are  still  open  to 

individuals  are  assembled.  [Here  the  first  method  is,  of  course,  the  one  adopted  ; 
for  the  second,  see  below,  §  72,  note. — Ed.] 

'  [Cf.  supra,  pp.  141,  142,  419.]  -  Theologische  Moral,  p.  394  f. 

3  1st  ed.  iii.  §  947  f. 


CHOICE  OF  A  VOCATION.  501 

them.  In  these  they  may  find,  to  their  own  benefit,  a  new 
vocation  adapted  to  their  powers,  and  be  supported  by  the 
experience  of  age  and  the  respect  accorded  to  it.  Therefore  let 
every  man  have  a  calling  (1  Cor.  vii.  20  ;  Matt.  xxv.  15). 

3.  It  is  a  more  difficnlt  matter,  however,  to  say  anything 
definite  regarding  the  cJioicc  of  a  vocation.  If  a  wrong  choice 
is  made,  it  is  a  serious  misfortune  both  for  the  individual 
himself  and  for  the  community.  When  the  life  of  a  man  is  a 
failure  so  far  as  his  vocation  is  concerned,  his  own  inward 
moral  development  is  rendered  more  difficult,  while  the  com- 
munity is  deprived  of  a  member  in  the  place  where  he  ought 
to  be,  and  at  the  same  time  is  furnished  with  a  member  in 
the  wrong  place.  He  thus  acts  as  a  hindrance  and  check  to 
the  free  movement  of  the  whole.  Accordingly,  the  utmost 
conscientiousness  and  strictest  self-examination  are  necessary 
here.  From  a  moral  point  of  view,  the  most  dangerous  thing 
of  all  is  to  enter  upon  the  clerical  or  theological  vocation 
without  an  inward  call.  For  since  this  vocation  rests  upon 
religious  enthusiasm  and  love,  hypocrisy  can  hardly  be  avoided 
where  the  inner  call  is  wanting.  On  the  other  hand,  when 
the  requisite  gifts  are  forthcoming,  it  is  the  easiest  and,  so  to 
speak,  the  most  natural  A'ocation.  For  that  which  is  the 
universal  Christian  duty  is  here  made,  only  because  of  the 
possession  of  the  necessary  talents,  the  special  duty.  This 
vocation  has  a  peculiar  dignity.  It  stands  among  others  like 
Sunday  among  the  days  of  the  week.  None  of  the  other 
professions,  indeed,  is  deprived  of  fellowship  with  God  ;  each 
one  catches  and  reflects  some  ray  of  Divine  light.  But  in  the 
clerical  vocation  a  man  is  professionally  occupied  with  the  sun 
itself.  Should  the  student,  moreover,  fall  into  doubt  with 
regard  to  the  faith,  this  must  not  lead  him  astray.  It  is  just 
when  he  is  anxious  about  his  truthfulness,  that  he  is  specially 
fitted  for  this  line  of  study.  No  more  is  required  of  him 
than  would  still  be  requisite  w^ere  he  to  abandon  his  profession, 
if  he  desires  to  continue  a  Christian.  Doubt  with  regard  to 
Christianity  must  become  doubt  with  regard  to  salvation.  But 
such  doubt  can,  nay,  ought  to  be  changed  by  every  one  into  full 
assurance  of  faith ;  and  this  change  takes  place  in  a  practical 
way,  not  by  means  of  demonstration.  If  by  faith  he  has  only 
the   elements  of  Christian  truth,  he  has  that  knowledge  and 


502  §   G8.    CONTINUATION. 

certainty  which  is  the  fouudation  of  every  other,  and  starting 
from  this  all  other  doubts  will  gradually  be  cleared  away/ 

The  moral  cJioice  of  a  vocation  in  general  is  made  through 
an  act  of  an  individual  kind,  in  which  a  decision  is  arrived  at 
on  purely  individual  grounds,  subject  to  the  direction  of  con- 
science. Thus  there  is  a  side  to  the  choice  of  a  vocation, 
which  is  altogether  removed  from  the  judgment  of  others  ; 
nevertheless,  from  an  ethical  point  of  view,  one  additional 
remark  of  a  general  nature  may  be  made.  The  good,  which 
forms  the  sphere  of  each  separate  vocation,  has  ever  been 
already  realized  in  the  course  of  history,  though  the  division 
of  labour  must  still  go  on.  The  manifold  varieties  of 
vocation  and  of  work  already  realized  make  it  possible  for 
every  person,  by  careful  survey  and  comparison,  to  arrive  at  a 
self-knowledge  which,  if  it  is  only  sufficiently  aroused,  will  of 
itself  become  a  knowledge  of  what  his  vocation  ought  to  be. 
Still  it  is  a  dangerous  thing  for  any  one  (a)  to  follow  solely 
his  inward  inclination,  without  receiving  the  consent  of  that 
objective  sphere  of  life  to  which  he  is  inclined,  by  means  of 
those  who  are  authorities  in  that  sphere.  To  do  so  is  to 
follow  what  Schleiermacher  calls  the  maxim  of  Lilertinism. 
On  the  other  hand,  it  is  just  as  false,  and  even  immoral  (&),  to 
be  guided  by  mere  external  calls  and  grounds  of  decision, 
^\hen  there  is  an  inward  reluctance  (cf.  chapter  on  Marriage). 
Accordingly,  to  carry  on  a  profession  for  the  mere  sake  of 
making  a  liveliliood  is  ethically  reprehensible.  This  is  what 
Schleiermacher  calls  the  maxim,  of  Cynicism.  It  is  immoral, 
because  here  that  very  thing  is  wanting  which  must  be  the 
animating  principle  of  all  productive  work — viz.  pleasure  in 
and  love  for  our  profession.  Class  divisions,  e.g.,  which 
compel  men  to  adopt  particular  vocations,  have  a  mechanizing 
tendency  and  are  immoral.  In  the  choice  of  a  vocation,  if  one 
of  the  two  factors  (the  objective  and  subjective)  should,  how- 
ever, have  less  influence  than  the  other,  love  for  our  vocation 
must  at  all  events  never  be  wanting.  It  is  the  first  requisite, 
even  in  point  of  time ;  for  in  the  case  of  many  professions,  the 
necessary  preparation  would  be  quite  impossible,  unless  it 
could  be  made  upon  the  foundation  of  subjective  inclination. 
Objective  approval  from  the  side  of  that  sphere  of  life  in  which 

1  Cf.  Glaiihenslehre,  i.  §  10. 


MOKAL  CHOICE  OF  A  VOCATION.  503 

our  vocation  lies  comes  afterwards.  Besides,  there  are  alway.s 
new  vocations  to  be  discovered.^  It  may  also  happen  that 
experienced  and  friendly  persons  do  not  express  their  opinion, 
but  that  we  are  nevertheless  able  to  anticipate  the  rational 
will  of  the  community  from  our  knowledge  of  its  needs.  Only 
thus  much,  therefore,  can  be  laid  down  ;  our  decision  must 
never  be  a  merely  subjective  one,  nor,  on  the  other  hand,  must 
love  and  inclination  ever  be  wanting ;  in  some  way  or  other, 
inward  impulse  and  an  outward  call  must  always  go  together. 

Note. — No  vocation  that  is  taken  up  for  mere  display  admits 
of  an  ethical  construction.  Such  professions  as  those  of  the 
acrobat,  the  juggler,  the  dancer,  or  those  for  the  exhibition 
of  physical  dexterity,  grace,  or  beauty,  do  not  exist  so  far 
as  ethics  are  concerned,  for  they  only  consume  and  do  not  pro- 
duce. These  are  the  breadless  (hrotlos)  arts,  so  called  because 
it  is  only  occasionally  that  they  yield  daily  bread,  and  because 
many  are  ruined  in  them  ;  but  in  addition  to  this  they  have  no 
ethical  basis.  The  case  is  somewhat  different  with  regard  to  the 
drama.  The  life  of  the  actor  may  degenerate  into  the  mere 
playing  of  a  part,  in  which  he  loses  his  own  individuality,  and 
may  thus  become  mere  di.splay  and  notliing  more.  A  man  may 
act  the  part  of  a  hero,  and  be  so  pleased  with  it,  and  so  lose  him- 
self in  it,  that  he  becomes  a  hero  in  his  own  thoughts.  But  this 
is  inartistic  as  well  as  unethical.  Art  demands  that  one  should 
assume  an  objective  attitude  to  the  part  he  plays,  and  never  sink 
his  self-consciousness  in  his  part.  To  do  the  opposite  is  as 
unseemly  as  it  is  unethical,  for  the  sphere  of  art  is  the  sphere 
of  beautiful  appearances.  But  when  the  actor  takes  up  the 
stage  as  his  life's  vocation,  he  runs  a  great  risk.  It  is  no 
^\'onder  that  the  Christian  Church  has  never  been  willing 
to  regard  acting  as  a  legitimate  vocation,  however  friendly 
it  may  be  to  the  art  itself.  Classic  antiquity  during  its  prime 
in  Athens  had  the  dramas  —  tragedies  —  but  no  professional 
actors.^ 

^  E.g.  Wichern  originated  a  vocation  that  had  no  existence  before  his  time. 
■  [As  supplementary  to  what  is  here  said,  cf.  the  chapter  on  Art.] 


504 


CHAPTER  THIRD. 

THE  CHKISTIAN  IN  KELATION  TO  OTHERS,  OR  THE  LOVE  OF  ONE'S 
NEIGHBOUR  IN  GENERAL. 

§  69. 

Christian  love  to  one's  neighbour  is  derived,  like  self-love, 
from  love  to  God ;  but  it  is  through  self-love  that  this 
derivation  takes  place.  On  its  negative  side,  again,  it 
takes  the  form  of  respect  or  justice,  on  its  positive  side 
it  is  love  in  the  form  of  kindness.  It  is  variously 
modified,  however,  in  the  different  social  spheres. 

The  Literature.  —  Rothe,  Thcologische  Ethik,  2nd  ed.  i. 
p.  500  f.,  1st  ed.  p.  380  f.,  iii.  pp.  252  f.,  452  f.  Martensen, 
ut  supra,  ii.  1,  p.  237  f.     Lemme,  Die  Nachstenliehc. 

1.  He  who  is  born  of  God,  loves  also  whatever  is  born  of 
Him  (1  John  v.  1),  by  a  kind  of  higher  natural  necessity, 
arising  from  the  kinship  of  the  new  creature  with  Christ. 
The  personality  formed  in  the  image  of  God  must  resemble 
God,  must  love  what  He  loves.  Self-love  and  love  of  one's 
neighbour  are  so  related  to  love  to  God,  that  the  latter 
demands  both  alike,  and  as  co-ordinate  the  one  with  the  other. 
For  that  which  sanctions  self-love  in  the  Christian — namely, 
the  value  of  the  new  person  in  the  eyes  of  God — also  makes 
the  love  of  his  brother  binding  upon  him.  In  point  of  time, 
however,  self-love  must  precede  love  of  others,  for  the  new 
self-determining  person  mu,st  itself  exist  before  it  can  love 
others.  Express  exhortations  to  love  of  one's  neighbour  are 
given  in  Matt.  xxii.  39  f.  ;  Luke  x.  27,  31  ;  John  xiii.  34 
1  Cor.  xiii.;  Eph.  v.  2  ;  Col.  iii.  14;  Gal.  v.  14,  vi.  2 
1  Tim.  i.  5;  Jas.  ii.  8,  10;  1  John  iii.  11,  iv.  7-9,  ii.  10  f. 
1  Pet.  i.  22,  iii.  8,  9  ;  2  Pet.  i.  7  ;  Heb.  xiii.  1.  The  name 
given  it  is  not  ep(o<;,  in  which  the  sensual  side  predominates, 
but  ajaTrr)  (2  Pet.  i.  7)  ;  among  relatives,  ^iXoaTopyo'i  (Rom. 
xii.  10)  ;  while  ^LkaSeXcfyia  is  Christian  brotherly  love  (2  Pet. 
i.  7).  With  regard  to  a  non-Christian,  it  is  the  future  Chris- 
tian, the  Candidatus  viUe,  that  is  loved  in  him,  on  the  ground 


LOVE  OF  one's  neighbouk.  505 

that  Christ  loved  the  world  (Eom.  v,  15),  and  died  for  it. 
Since  Christian  love  for  others  flows  from  love  to  God,  it  can 
never  place  men  or  human  societies  higher  than  God.  And 
just  as  little  can  the  love  we  show  to  others  be  opposed  to 
Christian  self-love,  or  sanction  anything  that  involves  a  loss 
of  our  own  soul.  For  then  it  would  itself  cease  to  exist. 
But  there  is  a  gradation  in  the  measure  of  ardent  affection 
shown  in  Christian  love  for  others  (Gal.  vi.  1 0) ;  the  olKeioi  r?}? 
7ri(TT€0i<;  have  the  first  claim  upon  us  (1  Tim.  v.  8).  As  com- 
pared with  men  in  general,  moreover,  those  who  are  naturally 
connected  with  us  are  adjudged  to  have  stronger  claims  upon 
our  love  (Matt.  xv.  4;  Eom.  xii.  10;  1  Tim.  iii.  4,  v.  8). 
But  when  the  second  creation  has  taken  place,  all  the  rights 
of  natural  love  are  suspended  in  favour  of  Christian  love  for 
the  brethren  (Matt.  x.  37,  xii.  47-50  ;  Mark  iii.  32  f.,  x.  29  ; 
Luke  viii.  19  f).  It  receives  this  high  place  because  it  is 
born  anew  out  of  love  to  God,  wliicli  is  the  measure  and  rule 
of  all  love.  The  negation  involved  in  faith  presupposes  an 
ideal  severance  from  all  merely  natural  love  ;  but  when  once 
this  has  taken  place,  the  natural  love  that  subsists  between 
relatives  is  again,  and  in  a  higher  degree,  established  in  its 
rights. 

2.  Christian  social  love,  like  self-love,  has  both  a  negative 
and  a  positive  side.  On  the  one  hand  it  appears  as  respect  or 
justice,  on  the  other  as  positive  love,  i.e.  kindness,  '^prjarorrj^, 
and  these  must  never  be  invxtrdhj  separated.  Outwardly, 
however,  love  must  often  be  veiled  in  justice  ;  but  thougli  thus 
kept  in  restraint  so  far  as  manifestation  is  concerned,  it 
must  be  present  inwardly — nay,  it  is  love  itself  that  must 
impose  this  restraint.  Further,  since  it  is  directed  to  man- 
kind as  a  whole,  it  also  brings  into  requisition  in  due  order 
the  whole  nature  of  the  Christian.  On  the  side  of  feeling, 
(christian  love  for  others  appears  as  good-will ;  on  the  side  of 
knowledge,  as  cultured  public  spirit  (§  64)  ;  on  the  side  of 
will,  as  effort  for  the  common  welfare  (§  68)  (1  Cor.  xii.  7). 
It  is  the  Christian  vitality  of  the  generic  consciousness. 
Inspired  by  it,  the  Christian  seeks  to  have  fellowship  with 
his  fellow-men  as  far  as  possible  ;  at  first  inwardly,  by  cul- 
tivating good-will,  and  then  outwardly,  in  the  way  directed  by 
justice  and  wisdom,  which  are  immanent  in  love.     Love  gives 


50G  §  g;i.  love  of  one's  neighbour. 

the  impulse  to  social  intercourse,  and  in  doing  so  it  aims  at 
real  reciprocity,  for  otherwise  the  fellowship  would  only  be 
apparent,  there  would  only  be  a  desire  either  to  give  or  to 
receive.  Accordingly,  in  social  love  we  must  be  sincerely 
willing  hoth  to  give  and  receive,  no  matter  which  of  these  two 
elements  may  predominate.  Here  we  must — though  gradually 
and  not  too  hastily — give  ourselves  to  our  neighbour,  jMSi(  as 
wc  arc.  In  like  manner,  we  must  seek  to  unite  ourselves  to 
him  just  as  he  is.  That  is  to  say,  we  unite  ourselves  (a) 
positively  to  what  is  true  in  his  individuality,  so  far  as  it 
has  already  been  developed ;  and,  on  the  other  hand,  (6) 
negatively  to  that  which  mars  his  individuality,  so  that  our 
love  helps  to  set  free  the  true  ego  of  our  neighbour.  Chris- 
tian huvhility  here  becomes  modesty ;  we  do  not  regard  our- 
selves as  rich  and  having  need  of  nothing,  nor  overestimate 
ourselves  as  so  highly  endowed  as  to  be  meant  to  give  only 
and  not  to  receive.  For  there  is  nothing  that  does  more  to 
check  or  split  up  human  fellowship  than  self-conceit.  It  is 
contrary  to  justice  both  with  respect  to  God  and  our  fellow- 
creatures.  In  no  less  a  degree  would  it  be  opposed  to  justice 
and  to  the  sincerity  of  love,  if  our  sole  object  in  associating 
with  another  were  to  obtain  in  him  a  serviceable  instrument 
for  our  own  ends,  or  to  make  him  a  mere  copy  of  ourselves. 
On  the  contrary,  love  will  make  us  treat  our  fellow-man  as  a 
real  end  in  himself.  We  shall  always  entertain  a  sacred 
reverence  for  his  God-designed  peculiarity,  even  when  our 
love  to  him  is  communicative  rather  than  receptive.  True 
love  points  away  from  itself  to  Christ,  and  desires  only  that 
He  may  increase  (John  iii.  30).  Hence  Christian  love  for 
others  helps  to  strengthen  and  perfect  the  new  creation  in 
which  all  these  individual  differences  are  implanted.  Justice, 
which  grants  suum  cuiquc,  by  its  recognition  of  these,  that  is, 
of  what  is  pure  in  them,  helps  to  confirm  them ;  it  promotes 
the  development  of  the  various  individual  characteristics. 

Love  and  justice  might  here  seem  to  be  in  contradiction, 
since  the  former  seeks  by  means  of  mutual  giving  and  taking 
to  reconcile  existing  differences,  while  the  latter  aims  at  con- 
firming them.  But  love  will  never  seek  to  efface  any  dis- 
tinction that  justice  wishes  to  see  maintained.  Nothing  that 
is  pure  in  individuality  can   be  an  obstruction  to  love ;  on 


CAKE  ¥011  HIS  SPIRITUAL  WELFARE.  507 

the  contrary,  it  enriches  social  life,  §  G8.  1,  2.  Love  does 
not  seek  to  make  all  alike  ;  what  it  tries  to  do  is  to  make 
the  interest  of  one  the  interest  of  all,  to  make  us  regard  the 
joy  and  sorrow  of  another  as  our  own  (1  Cor.  iii.  22),  and  to 
enable  each  member  of  a  community,  although  he  does  not 
directly  possess  all  that  is  within  it,  to  enter  m  soone  degree 
into  the  enjoyment  of  everything,  and  so  to  feel  that  he  has 
a  share  in  everything.  On  the  other  side,  he  possesses  what 
is  his  for  others  also. 

3.  It  is  not  necessary  to  go  into  detail  as  to  the  separate 
ways  in  which  social  love  is  actively  carried  into  eftect. 
We  manifest  it  by  helping  our  fellow-men  to  promote  and 
care  for  tliose  goods  that  are  included  in  the  circle  of 
individual  life.  These  have  been  examined  with  some 
minuteness  in  §  57-68,  and  consist  of  such  goods  as  the 
body,  life,  health,  property,  good  name,  legitimate  influ- 
ence, outward  and  especially  inward  honour  and  our  voca- 
tion. There  are  just  two  points  on  which  we  will  dwell 
for  a  little.  Many,  who  in  other  respects  are  ready  to  make 
sacrifices  for  love's  sake,  frequently  omit  to  show  a  loving- 
care  for  the  so'ul  made  in  the  image  of  God,  and  thus  neglect 
to  promote  the  spiritual  welfare  of  their  fellow-men.  Such 
conduct,  if  it  does  not  arise  out  of  worldliness,  yet  involves 
the  secret  presupposition,  that  Clnistianity  is  not  equally 
necessary  for  all,  and  therefore  that  salvation  is  not  such  an 
absolute  requisite  for  all  as  food  and  clothing.  It  therefore 
implies  a  secret  doubt  whether  Christianity  is  as  necessary 
to  others  as  it  is  to  us,  and  whether  their  case  must  not  just 
be  left  to  the  ordinary  course  of  events.  But  persistently 
continued  silence  concerning  salvation  in  familiar  personal 
intercourse  with  others  may  become  a  denial  of  Christ,  may 
bring  to  a  standstill  that  productive  process  of  love  which,  as 
the  Christian  well  knows,  draws  its  energy  and  its  nourish- 
ment from  Christ.  The  decisive  means  of  counteracting  this 
error  is  the  practice  of  Christian  intercession.  When  the 
Christian  remembers  his  neighbour  before  the  throne  of  God, 
he  cannot  forget  his  spiritual  needs.  And  whatever  we 
earnestly  pray  for,  we  shall  work  for  too.  The  second  point 
refers  to  love  for  others  when  directed,  not  to  individuals, 
but  communities,  and  concerns  the  relation  that  subsists  in 


508  §  eo.  LOVE  OF  one's  neighbour. 

them  all  between  the  universal  and  the  'particular.  Here 
Christian  love  for  others  transcends  both  abstract  cosmopoli- 
tanism and  narrow  party  spirit.  For  it  holds  the  proper 
balance  between  the  universal-human  on  the  one  hand — 
which  in  its  essential  truth  is  the  universal-Christian — and 
particular  communities  on  the  other.  And  for  this  very 
reason  it  exerts  itself  to  maintain  a  living  fellowship  between 
individual  communities  (cf.  §  64).  The  cosmopolitan,  on  the 
contrary,  sets  little  store  by  his  own  particular  community  and 
depreciates  it  ;  he  stands  far  removed  from  the  actual  world, 
indulging  in  an  impotent  love  for  universal  humanity,  which 
naturally  dwells  more  in  a  realm  of  ideas  than  of  actions  ;  he 
has  therefore  no  spiritual  home,  and  evinces  neither  justice 
nor  love  towards  that  which  is  most  closely  related  to  him. 
The  opposite  extreme  is  that  oi  party  spirit,  which  seeks  to 
elevate  its  own  particular  community  at  the  expense  of  others, 
and  is  therefore  lacking  in  justice  and  love  towards  other 
communities.  Party  spirit  may  pervade  like  a  disease  the 
various  spheres  of  moral  life,  it  may  be  found  in  science  and 
art,  in  the  different  schools  and  tendencies  of  thought  ;  but 
it  has  always  taken  up  its  chosen  seat  in  the  regions  of  the 
State  and  the  Church,  and  is  seen  in  the  relations  of  individual 
States  and  Churches  to  each  other,  as  well  as  within  the  same 
State  or  the  same  section  of  the  Church.  It  is  not  the  true 
spirit  of  association,  nor  true  love  to  our  own  community, 
which  we  show  when  we  idolize  that  community,  deny  the 
gifts  that  have  been  bestowed  upon  others,  and  wind  up  a 
part  into  the  place  of  the  whole ;  such  proceeding  is  a  cari- 
cature of  churchmanship  ;  it  is  in  principle  sectarian,  even 
though  exhibited  by  a  great  Church  community.  For  the 
principle  of  sectarianism  is,  that  the  part  tries  to  swell  itself 
out  to  the  dimensions  of  the  whole,  and  forgets  catholicity 
for  its  own  particular  confession  or  national  Church.  Such 
party  spirit  is  exposed  to  great  moral  dangers  from  the  in- 
justice and  lovelessness  it  manifests  towards  others,  and  its 
contempt  for  the  gifts  which  have  been  conferred  upon  them, 
— gifts  which  were  by  no  means  meant  for  their  possessors 
alone,  but  which,  on  the  contrary,  are  needed  by  the  whole 
body  of  the  Church.  Further,  since  our  own  party  has 
become  a  mere  extension  of  our  individual  Ego,  the  deification 


ADJUSTMENT  OF  DISSIMILARITIES.  509 

of  it  is,  from  a  Christian  point  of  view,  only  an  intensified 
form  of  self-idolatry,  though  we  may  be  quite  unconscious  of 
the  fact.  Outwardly,  party  spirit  becomes  Egoism,  wliich 
may  even  take  the  negative  attitude  of  hatred.  Finally, 
party  spirit  in  the  Church,  and  elsewliere  too,  while  thus 
encroaching  upon  truth  and  Justice,  is  also  opposed  to  freedom, 
since  it  makes  us  more  or  less  dependent  upon  men  (1  Cor. 
vii.  23).  What  makes  the  Apostle  Paul  so  large-hearted  is, 
that  he  puts  all  Christians  alike  in  subjection  to  Christ,  and 
requires  them  to  consider  themselves  ixeXtj  XpiaTov.  He 
allows  Christ  to  be  preached  in  different  ways,  provided  only 
He  be  really  preached,  and  preached  as  eaTavp(o/u,€vo<i  (Phil. 
i.  15-18  ;  1  Cor.  ii.  2,  iii.  11-15).  And  the  history  of  the 
Church  and  of  doctrine  shows  that  there  is  never  perfect 
agreement  in  belief  or  in  the  apprehension  of  Christ,  but  that, 
on  the  contrary,  the  differences  which  exist  in  this  respect  are 
necessary  to  progress.  In  Eph.  iv.  13,  perfect  unity,  even  in 
the  apprehension  of  Christian  faith,  is  put  forward  as  a  goal  to 
be  attained,  not  as  something  to  be  required  at  present.  And 
notwithstanding  their  differences,  the  apostle  tells  his  readers 
that  they  belong  to  the  awfia  Xptcrrov.  Such  differences  as 
do  not  injure  the  Oep.ekio'^  are  borne  by  Christian  hope  in  the 
unity  of  the  spirit  of  love,  with  a  patience  which  is  not,  how- 
ever, indolent. 

4.  The  Dissimilarities  which  Christian  Brotherly  Love  strives 
to  adjust.  Some  of  these  dissimilarities  rest  upon  the  con- 
stitution of  the  world,  apart  from  sin  altogether  {e.g.  the 
difference  between  those  who  in  the  main  are  ill-provided 
with  regard  to  things  spiritual  and  physical,  and  those  who  are, 
on  the  other  hand,  capable  of  communicating),  while  others 
are  due  to  sin  ;  to  the  latter  class  belong  the  relations  involved 
in  strife. 

(a)  The  first  difference  arises  from  the  fact  that  the  older 
and  the  younger  generation,  §  17.  3,  parents  and  children, 
teachers,  masters  and  scholars,  exist  contemporaneously. 
Educational  influence  must  aim  at  something  more  than 
mere  equalization  ;  it  should  seek  to  make  the  coming 
generation  better  than  the  one  that  preceded  it.  Further, 
difference  of  talent  is  the  chief  ground  of  the  difference 
between  wealth  and  poverty.     And  Christian  love  for  others, 


510  §  G9.    LOVE  OF  one's  XEIGIIBOUE. 

in  endeavouring  to  eliminate  whatever  is  hurtful  and  disturbing 
in  the  condition  of  things,  introduces  the  relation  between 
'benefactor  and  hencficiary.  We  must  dwell  a  little  longer  on 
this  point — that  is,  on  love  for  others,  in  its  two  forms  of 
communicative  goodness  and  recipient  love,  or  gratitude 
(cf.  §  45.  5,  §  63.  3). 

The  difference  between  rich  and  poor  is  not  evil  in  itself. 
It  is  a  bond  of  fellowship,  an  opportunity  for  love  to  inter- 
pose and  adjust  inequalities  both  of  a  material  and  spiritual 
kind.  The  loving  bestowal  of  material  gifts  upon  those  who 
are  in  want  is  called  beneficence  (2  Cor.  ix.  11-14).  Every 
act  of  charity  is  a  God  -  appointed  way  of  using  external 
circumstances  to  bring  men  inwardly  into  closer  connection. 
The  ijift  is  meant  to  be  the  means  of  forming;  a  moral  bond 
between  giver  and  receiver.  But  this  end  is  not  gained 
by  merely  giving  away  to  hegga^rs.  Begging  was  forbidden  in 
the  Old  Testament  (Deut.  xv.  4),  and  it  has  still  less  right  to 
exist  in  Christendom.  It  should  be  unnecessary.  There  is 
enough  work  and  material  for  all,  if  only  love  and  industry 
be  not  wanting.  There  is  something  sacred  in  poverty. 
The  poor  are  the  altar  of  the  Church.  But  there  is  notliing 
sacred  ctbout  begging.  It  injures  personal  dignity,  leads  to 
lying,  deceit,  and  sloth,  and  to  an  irregular  and  thoughtless 
way  of  living.  Indiscriminate  almsgiving  increases  all  these 
vices,  as  is  shown  on  a  large  scale  in  the  Eomish  Church, 
[t  is  the  part  of  the  Evangelical  Church,  since  it  lays  such 
stress  on  the  honour  and  dignity  of  the  Christian  personality, 
to  make  regulations  for  the  relief  of  the  poor,  and  thus  to 
eradicate  the  practice  of  begging,  which  is  a  symptom  of 
disease  in  a  community.  Voluntary  efforts  must  also  be 
made  for  this  purpose.  It  has  a  pernicious  effect  when  the 
case  of  the  poor  is  assigned  to  the  sphere  of  law  alone  (§  34«, 
03.  2).  Socialistic  and  communistic  theories  would  fain 
(§  63,  Note)  secure,  by  means  of  law  and  compulsory  power, 
that  which  only  love  can  accomplish,  viz.  the  adjustment 
of  crying  inequalities.  Bid  the  absolute  removal  of  these 
inequalities  must  not  be  thought  of.  Every  attempt  in  this 
direction,  by  means  of  a  division  of  goods,  would  not  only  be  a 
wrong  to  the  rights  of  property  (§  63),  but  would  also  be  a 
failure ;  for  differences  would  at  once  break  out  again,  since 


ADJUSTMENT  OF  DISSIMILARITIES.  511 

they  have  their  ground  in  difference  of  talent,  of  industry, 
and  of  character.  Moreover,  there  would  be  no  room  left  for 
either  love  or  gratitude.  Gifts  would  be  demanded  as  a  right, 
and  the  spirit  of  egoism  would  be  pampered.  Universal 
impoverishment  and  mendicity  would  be  the  result.  There 
was  no  compulsion  exercised  in  the  Church  of  Jerusalem 
(Acts  V.  1  ff.) ;  there  was  only  perfect  willingness  to  put  pro- 
perty at  the  disposal  of  the  apostles  for  the  common  benefit.  No 
division  of  goods  took  place,  nor  was  such  division  generally 
carried  out;  but  gifts  were  put  into  a  common  treasury,  out 
of  which  cases  of  necessity  were  relieved  (Acts  ii.  45). 

But  a  word  or  tv)o  in  addition  must  he  said  on  right  giving 
oAul  right  receiving. 

(a)  When  we  give  rightly,  we  do  not  seek  to  make  our 
fellow-men  dependent  upon  us,  but  leave  them  free.  To 
demand  thanks  is  an  odious  thing.  Christian  charity,  too, 
does  not  wish  to  be  seen,  Matt.  vi.  1  f. ;  it  gives  simply — 
that  is  to  say,  it  has  nothing  in  view  but  the  actual  need 
before  it.  It  does  not  ask  the  needy  whether  they  are 
worthy  (Matt.  v.  45)  or  deserving ;  but  neither  does  it  give 
in  a  way  that  would  prove  injurious.  Just  as  little  does  it 
give  for  the  purpose  of  getting  rid  of  the  poor.  For  in  that 
case  the  gift  would  lack  that  which  is  its  salt;  a  real  interest 
in,  or  respect  for,  the  recipient  as  a  personal  being.  It  is 
enough  that  the  giver  has  through  his  position  a  certain 
advantage ;  he  must  not  make  the  recipient  feel  his  depend- 
ence as  well.  When  a  Christian  gives,  he  puts  himself  by 
sympathy  in  the  place  of  the  sufferer,  regards  him  as  a 
member  of  the  whole ;  and  thus  his  help  is  divested  of 
everything  that  might  offend  the  self-respect  of  the  recipient. 
All  that  is  here  required  is  summed  up  in  the  injunction, 
fieTuBiSovac,  ev  d'rrXorrjTc  (Eom.  xii.  8).  When  an  act  of 
beneficence  on  the  part  of  Christ  is  recorded,  it  is  often 
added — He  was  moved  with  compassion. 

(/3)  The  other  side  of  Christian  love  for  others  is  thank- 
fulness. In  a  certain  sense,  indeed,  it  may  be  said  that  it  is 
to  God  alone  that  we  owe  thanks.  We  may  justly  have 
some  scruples  about  giving  thanks  to  men.  God's  gifts 
honour  and  ennoble  us ;  but  human  gifts  may  reduce  us  to  a 
condition  of  dependence,  and  have  an  enslaving  effect.     It  is 


512  §  GO.    LOVE  OF  one's  NEIGHBOUR. 

better  not  to  accept  such  benefits  as  damage  our  personal 
independence.  In  expressing  our  thanks  to  our  benefactor, 
moreover,  we  may  very  possibly  do  so  in  a  way  that  acknow- 
ledges such  a  dependence  upon  him  as  we  ought  to  feel 
towards  God  alone,  or  we  may  treat  him  as  if  he  had 
bestowed  his  kindness  of  his  own  favour  and  goodwill. 
When  those  who  give  have  done  so  in  a  pious  spirit,  their 
act  carries  our  thoughts  away  from  themselves  to  God  as  the 
giver ;  but  when  they  have  not  given  from  love  to  God,  but 
from  egoism,  however  refined  it  may  be,  then  in  so  doing 
they  would  seem  to  have  forfeited  all  reward  in  the  shape  of 
gratitude.  Nevertheless  thankfulness  towards  men  rests  on 
good  grounds  when  we  regard  them  as  persons,  who  in  spon- 
taneous love  and  for  our  benefit  seek  to  make  themselves  the 
instruments  of  Divine  love.  In  gratitude  towards  men,  there- 
fore, gratitude  towards  God  nuist  certainly  be  present  and 
occupy  the  chief  place.  When  this  is  the  case,  the  loving 
will  of  God  is  also  honoured,  since  by  means  of  the  gift  it 
has  brought  the  giver  into  closer  connection  with  us.  When 
God  brings  two  persons  into  the  relation  of  giver  and 
receiver.  He  has  formed  between  them  a  moral  bond  of 
love  of  a  special  kind.  And  to  break  this  bond,  instead  of 
making  it  a  mutual  one  by  responding  with  love  on  our  side, 
or  to  accept  the  gift  while  we  impugn  or  suspect  the  love 
that  is  in  it,  is  a  base  thing.  Mistrust  is  loveless  and  a  sin. 
Thankfulness  consists  in  keeping  in  mind  the  love  we  have 
experienced ;  to  thank  is  the  frequentative  of  to  think.  The 
giver,  indeed,  has  an  advantage  over  the  recipient  to  begin 
with,  in  so  far  as  it  is  more  blessed  to  give  than  to  receive ; 
but  the  latter  will  be  quite  satisfied  that  it  should  be  so,  if 
only  he  believes  that  love  is  at  the  bottom  of  the  gift ;  and 
this  it  is  his  duty  to  do,  unless  it  is  openly  manifest  that  the 
opposite  is  the  case.  For  to  know  that  any  one  has  loved 
us  before  any  advances  on  our  part  is  not  degrading,  but 
ennobling,  since  we  see  that  his  love  has  been  freely  bestowed. 
And  for  this  very  reason  grateful  love  does  not  seek  to  pay 
or  recompense  the  love  that  has  been  evinced,  but  to  respond 
to  it.  Love  as  the  fruit  of  freedom  is  an  infinite  good, 
it  is  absolutely  invaluable.  In  the  eyes  of  love,  only  love 
in  return  is  of  equal  value  with  itself. 


LOVE  TO  OUR  NEIGHBOUR.  513 

(b)  With  regard  to  the  settlement  of  the  disturhances  which 
sin  occasions  in  the  relation  of  one  man  to  another,  that  is 
to  say,  with  regard  to  strife  between  private  individuals,  the 
New  Testament  enjoins  the  love  of  peace  (Mark  ix.  50 ; 
Jas.  iii.  17).  The  Christian  prevents  strife  by  doing  justice 
and  showing  respect  to  his  fellow-men,  by  being  amicable  and 
peaceable  (Matt.  v.  5  f.).  He  will  rather  suffer  wrong  than  do  it. 
When  brought  into  strife  against  his  will,  he  exhibits  meek- 
ness and  gentleness,  Trpaorrjq,  i'TTteiKeia  (Gal.  v.  2-3  ;  2  Cor. 
X.  1;  cf.  Col.  iii.  12;  1  Tim.  vi.  11).  When  the  strife  is 
over,  he  exhibits  love  by  his  readiness  to  forgive  and  be 
reconciled  (Luke  vii.  41  f . ;  Matt.  vi.  12,  xviii.  32  f . ;  Eph. 
iv,  32  ;  Col.  iii.  13).  For  even  love  to  enemies  is  com- 
manded ;  the  Christian  is  no  man's  enemy,  he  is  only 
passively  involved  in  e-^^dpa.  It  deserves  serious  considera- 
tion, how  our  Lord  makes  the  forgiveness  of  our  sins  depend 
upon  whether  we  ourselves  forgive.  Placability  is  the  negative 
condition  of  our  sacrifices  being  well-pleasing  to  God  (Matt, 
v.  24,  vi.  12).  And  why  ?  Because  he  who  will  not  forgive 
his  brother  shows  that  he  is  insensible  to  the  much  greater 
debt  he  owes  to  God,  and  therefore  impenitent  (Matt, 
xviii.  23  f.).  Further,  Christ  enforces  the  duty  of  placa- 
bility upon  His  disciples,  because  nothing  does  more  to 
destroy  the  efficacy  of  Christianity  in  the  world,  and  to 
extenuate  the  antagonism  of  the  world  to  the  gospel,  than 
want  of  love  in  the  conduct  of  believers  toward  each  other. 
For  it  is  the  power  of  love  proceeding  from  believers,  that  is 
intended  to  be  the  specific  means  of  attracting  the  world  to 
Christ  as  the  source  of  salvation  and  love,  and  to  convince 
the  world  that  Christ  was  sent  by  God  (John  xvii.  23).  At 
the  same  time,  it  is  not  required  that  Christians  should  call 
black  white,  or  light  darkness.  No  fact  must  be  surrendered. 
To  do  so  would  betray  indifferentism  (§§  55,  66)  or  partiality, 
and  would  lead  to  a  dishonourable  peace.  But  all  strife 
between  Christians  about  a  fact  ought  certainly  to  exhibit 
meekness,  moderation,  and  justice ;  and  ingenuity  is  much 
better  employed  by  love  in  trying  to  put  the  best  con- 
struction on  everything,  and  discovering  means  for  coming  to 
an  understanding,  than  in  hunting  up  excuses  for  keeping 
apart  (1  Cor.  i.-iii.),  or  in  finding  food  for  mistrust. 

2  K 


514  §  70.    SOCIAL  INTEECOUriSE. 

§  70.  Social  InUrcour&e, 

The  fellowship  into  which  Christian  love  brings  us  with  our 
fellow-men  (§  69),  when  it  does  not  take  an  organized 
shape,  but  nevertheless  is  something  more  than  mere 
momentary  and  accidental  contact,  is  the  sphere  of  social 
intercourse,  and  forms  the  transition  from  social  duties 
in  general  to  settled  Christian  communities. 

1.  Social  intercourse  is  the  indispensable  antecedent  of 
all  ethical  communities,  the  preliminary  of  their  genesis  or 
reproduction.  Standing  midway  between  individuals  wholly 
unconnected  with  each  other  and  organized  forms  of  social 
life,  it  is  a  means  of  supply  for  matrimony,  art,  and  science. 
In  this  region,  too,  all  great  advances  in  the  State  and  the 
Church  have  their  true  birthplace,  more  especially  in  friend- 
ships of  the  higher  kind — heroic,  as  distinguished  from  merely 
"  romantic  "  friendships.  For  the  former  have  their  bond  of 
union  in  an  objective  ethical  aim,  to  be  realized  by  action ; 
their  object  is  not  simply  ideal  enjoyment.  At  the  same 
time,  we  must  not  forget  that  social  intercourse  has  also 
another  side  (§§  61,  62).  It  is  meant  to  afford  enjoyment 
and  recreation,  and  thus  belongs  to  tlie  sphere  of  self-love 
and  self-duty ;  but  in  such  wise  that  love  for  others  has  its 
place  also,  since  we  may  not  make  use  of  our  neighbour 
simply  as  a  means.  Here,  too,  it  is  inclination,  love,  that 
must  keep  men  together ;  otherwise  there  is  no  real  exchange 
of  good  offices,  but  only  giving  on  one  side  and  receiving  on 
the  other ;  or,  at  all  events,  something  quite  different  from 
recreation  and  enjoyment  is  manifested. 

2.  Social  intercourse,  moreover,  has  also  its  position  within 
organized  communities  themselves.  These,  if  they  are  to  con- 
tinue in  a  healthy  state,  must  call  it  into  being  from  them- 
selves. For  it  is,  as  it  were,  the  womb  out  of  which  their 
future  prosperity  is  born ;  or  the  vehicle  and  source  of  a 
public  opinion,  which  must  send  its  purifying  and  refreshing 
streams  through  the  barriers  that  divide  the  special  department 
of  each  separate  community.  In  family  life  this  is  realized 
by  means  oi  family  friendships,  and  the  relations  of  guest  and 
host :  in  science  and  art,  as  well  as  in  State  and  Church,  by 


"VOLUNTARY  ASSOCIATIONS.  515 

means  of  voluntary  societies.  It  is  narrow-minded  on  the 
part  of  an  organized  community,  and  destructive  of  the  germs 
of  its  own  future,  to  regard  associations  of  this  kind  existing 
within  its  pale  as  objects  merely  of  anxiety  and  jealousy,  or 
to  strive  to  absorb  them  into  itself,  and  to  restrict  their  due 
activity.  But,  on  the  other  side,  such  associations  become 
immoral  when  they  seek  to  take  in  hand  the  tasks  which 
devolve  upon  an  organized  community  as  a  whole,  and  would 
thus  place  themselves  as  secondary  suns  in  the  position  of  the 
latter — as  a  State  within  the  State,  or  a  Church  within  the 
Church.  In  the  Church  this  applies  to  all  the  voluntary  societies 
that  at  present  exist,  and  in  particular,  to  pastoral  conferences. 
(3n  the  contrary,  organized  bodies  are  always  higher  than 
independent  associations ;  each  of  them  is  the  strictly  respon- 
sible vehicle  of  its  own  idea,  and  hence  the  latter  must 
always  be  in  harmony  with  them,  must  respect  them,  and  not 
attempt  to  govern  them ;  otherwise  voluntary  association 
results  in  the  formation  of  pernicious  coalitions,  in  which 
men  seek  to  play  the  part  of  a  State  within  the  State,  or  a 
city  within  the  city ;  and  their  association  with  each  other, 
which  is  in  itself  harmless  and  of  general  benefit,  is  perverted 
to  purposes  of  intrigue,  conspiracy,  etc.  In  a  community, 
therefore,  each  voluntary  association  must  devote  itself  to 
only  one  particular  object,  and  must  not  seek  to  occupy  the 
whole  of  the  sphere  to  which  it  stands  related.  Only  under 
this  limitation  do  they  exert  a  wholesome  influence :  it  keeps 
them  flexible  as  well  as  living  and  powerful,  and  though  their 
life  may  be  short  it  leaves  behind  it  fruitful  furrows.  Free- 
masonry is  an  association  that  cannot  be  ethically  approved 
of;  for,  in  the  first  place,  it  is  not  flexible,  and  then  it  is  a 
secret  society,  disengaged  from  public  national  life,  and  inclined 
to  abstract  cosmopolitanism,  which  is  often  closely  allied  to 
indifferentism.  It  is  impossible  to  see  how  we  can  become 
members  of  such  an  association  in  a  moral  way.  For  its  aims 
are  shrouded  in  mystery,  and  hence  the  extent  of  the  promise 
demanded  on  entering  cannot  be  known  before  we  bind  our- 
selves by  it. 


516  §  71.  SUMMARY. 

THIRD   DIVISION. 

THE  ORGANIZED  WORLD  OF  CHRISTIAN  MORALITY,  OR  THE  MORAL 
COMMUNITIES  IN  THE  KINGDOM  OF  GOD. 

§  71.   Summary.      The  Kingdom  of  God. 

The  highest  Good,  which  exists  originally  in  the  Triune  God 
revealed  in  Christ  (§§  6,  V,  39-42),  and  derivatively  in 
the  individual  personality  (§§  43-70),  reaches  full  de- 
velopment as  a  power  in  the  world,  in  the  various 
moral  communities,  which  are  organically  connected 
with  each  other  in  the  same  way  as  the  divine  attri- 
butes,^ of  which  they  are  copies.  The  unity  or  total 
organism  formed  by  these  communities  is  the  Kingdom 
of  Crod  (civitas  Dei)  (§  31).  Accordingly,  the  organic 
construction  of  the  latter  corresponds  with  the  leading 
categories  in  the  idea  of  God  (§§  6,  7),  and  in  conformity 
with  its  foundation  in  the  individual  personality  formed 
in  God's  image  (§  56,  p.  445).  Thus  we  have  the 
following  three  main  portions  : — 

Division  I.  The  fundamental  moral  community,  or  the 
household  (§§  17.  3,  18,  33a,  34a).  Here 
we  shall  consider — 1.  Marriage;  2.  The 
Family ;  and  3.  The  Extension  of  Family 
Life  by  Friendship  and  Hospitality,  and  by 
the  relations  between  Masters  and  Servants. 
Division  II.  The  special  communities  that  have  been  created 
by  reflection  or  human  skill  (§§  17,  18,  33a, 
34a).  1.  The  State,  §§  17,  18,  33a,  34a 
(§  23).  2.  Art,  §§  17,  38a  (61,  62).  3. 
Science,  §§  17,  33a. 
Division  III.  The  Absolute  or  Eeligious  Community  (§§  31, 
33a,  34a). 

The  self-reproduction  and  self-preservation  of  the  life  of  the 
human  race  are  promoted  by  the  family  or  the  household,  which  is 
1  Cf.  Glaubenskhre,  i.  §§  22-27,  32. 


THE  KINGDOM  OF   GOD,  517 

the  fundamental  moral  community.  Divine  justice,  hecmty,  and 
ivisdom,  are  reflected  in  the  particular  moral  spheres  of  the  State, 
Art,  and  Seience  respectively;  while  the  reflection  of  the  Divine 
love  is  presented  in  the  absolute  or  religious  community,  the 
Church.  Each  of  these  spheres  embraces,  in  its  own  way,  all 
the  others,  and  takes  an  interest  in  them,  according  to  its 
own  particular  principle ;  each  one,  therefore,  is  also  embraced 
by  all  the  rest.  Thus  they  penetrate,  without  intermingling 
with  each  other,  advancing  in  an  orbit  of  the  spirit  of  love  in 
its  diversified  manifestations,  in  an  ethic  Trept^oipT^o-/?.  Not- 
withstanding the  unity  of  all  these  spheres — a  unity  main- 
tained by  each  one  promoting  the  well-being  of  the  rest 
— each  continues  to  be  an  end  to  itself ;  and  notwithstanding 
tlieir  independence  of  each  other, — an  independence  maintained 
by  each  having  its  own  distinct  principle, — they  yet  remain 
means  for  one  another. 

The  Literatuke. — Martensen,  ut  supra,  i.  32  f.,  147  f  ;  iii.  pp. 
1  f.,  306  f.,  348  f.  Eitschl,  Rechtfertigung  und  Versolinung,  iii. 
ch.  4.  Krauss,  Das  Dogma  von  der  unsichtharen  Kirchc,  p. 
142  f.     A.  Dorner,  Kirchc  und  Reich  Gottes.] 

Note. — It  is  true  that  the  individual  p)erson  is  made  in  the 
image  of  God,  and  is  thus  a  copy  of  the  divine  nature  in  its 
totality ;  but  tliis  he  is  imperfectly,  and  under  the  limitations 
inseparable  from  the  individual.  A  higher  representation  of 
the  Divine  is  reached  in  the  following  way.  By  reason  of 
the  individual  differences  that  exist  among  men,  especially 
when  these  are  concentrated  upon  definite  objects  and  thus 
become  talents  (§  G8),  the  one  moral  organism  becomes  a  unity 
made  up  of  many  members,  each  of  which  is  an  organism  with 
its  own  peculiar  principle  and  its  independence,  while,  never- 
theless, they  cannot  deny  their  essential  connection  with  each 
other.  All  these  principles,  indeed,  as  well  as  their  products, 
already  exist  in  germ  in  every  individual  personality — nay, 
more,  are  rooted  in  personality  and  draw  from  it  their  nourish- 
ment ;  but  these  piinciples  do  not  receive  their  fully  developed, 
that  is,  their  world-wide  manifestation,  until  the  whole  of 
humanity  has  formed  itself  into  an  organism  built  up  of  com- 
munities distinct  from  each  other,  yet  distinct  in  such  a  way 
that  the  principle  of  each  of  them  includes  the  whole  of 
humanity  within  its  scope.  These  principles,  it  may  again  be 
said  (cf  p.  500,  note),  become  so  many  centres  of  attraction 
gathering  men  around  them,  each  according  to  that  side  of  his 


518  §  71.    SUMMARY. 

nature  wliich  is  in  sympathy  with  each  of  these  communities ; 
and  thus  every  individual  may  belong,  by  different  sides  of  his 
nature,  to  several,  or  even  to  all  of  them,  though  in  varying 
degree,  according  to  his  endowments.  [In  some  he  will  be 
merely  receptive,  in  others  he  will  be  productive  and  find 
a  vocation.]  If,  therefore,  each  personality  is  ^:'<:r  sc  a  copy 
of  the  Divine  attributes,  much  more  does  the  whole  of  humanity, 
as  an  organism  made  up  of  many  different  moral  communities, 
present  us  with  a  living  picture  of  the  Godhead,  as  it  mirrors 
itself  in  the  creature.  In  the  first  part  of  this  work  we  have 
already  spoken  of  the  natural  genesis  of  these  communities, 
through  the  combined  operation  of  universal  and  individual 
capacities,  and  we  have  likewise  seen  the  modifications  they 
undergo  on  the  stage  of  right.  On  the  Christian  stage,  the 
religious  community  is  added  to  the  others,  and  all  of  them 
together,  when  comprehended  in  one  whole,  form  the  kingdom 
of  God.  jNIoreover,  the  individual  members  of  these  com- 
munities or  moral  persons  are,  through  their  connection  with 
them,  elevated  to  a  higher  stage  of  personal  morality  (§  68.  1). 
For,  being  inspired  by  the  spirit  of  the  whole,  they  are  thus 
raised  to  a  higher  degree  of  moral  power,  since  in  them  the 
universal  and  the  individual  have  now  reached  that  penetration 
of  each  other  intended  by  God. 

1.  In  the  New  Testament,  the  phrase  "  Kingdom  of 
God"  is  used,  not  in  an  ideal  sense  to  denote  something 
merely  subjective  or  internal.  It  is  true  that  the  subject, 
the  individual  person,  is  the  first  element  of  its  earthly  exist- 
ence ;  but  it  is  itself  the  whole  system  of  ethical  organisms 
destined  to  come  to  objective  appearance.  Of  these  no  par- 
ticular one  must  be  singled  out  above  the  rest,  and  made  the 
one  that  alone  embraces  all  the  others.  Eoman  Catholicism, 
indeed,  puts  the  Church  in  the  place  of  the  kingdom  of  God, 
(§  31) — a  doctrine  which  the  Eeformation  opposes.  Within 
Protestantism  a  tendency  has  appeared — especially  where  the 
State  takes  the  form  of  bureaucratic  absolutism  and  territori- 
alism — to  give  this  position  of  superiority  to  the  State.  The 
Hegelian  philosophy,  in  particular,  has  advanced  the  theor}" 
that  the  State  is  the  Ail  of  morality.  Among  distinguished 
theologians,  Eothe  approaches  nearest  to  this  view — at  first  in 
his  book  Die  Anfdnge  der  christlichen  Kirche,  and  then  in  a  more 
finished  and  careful  form  in  his Ethik^  [also  in  his  Encyhlopadie^]. 

'  1st  ed.  i.  §§  273-285  ;  iii.  §  1156  f.,  p.  900  f. 
-  [Encyklopadte,  edited  by  Ruppelius,  pp.  83-94.] 


THE  CHURCH  AND  THE  STATE.  519 

He  would  have  the  State  regarded  as  the  realization  of 
the  perfect  moral  community.  The  State  must  set  nothing 
less  than  this  before  itself  as  its  aim.  Its  mission 
is  (i.  p.  424)  simply  to  become  the  universal  and  absolute 
community,  that  is,  the  religious  and  moral  community 
which  embraces  all  men  and  all  departments  of  life. 
Until  the  close,  howevei',  of  its  moral  development  (§  279), 
the  moral  community,  of  which  the  State  is  as  yet  only 
the  imperfect  realization,  requires  to  be  supplemented  by 
the  religious  community  as  such,  the  religious  community 
pure  and  simple,  that  is,  the  Church.  The  reason  of 
this  is,  that  during  the  process  of  development  {not,  indeed, 
morality  and  religion,  but)  the  moral  community  and  the 
religious,  differ  from  each  other  as  regards  the  extent  of  the 
spheres  which  they  embrace.  The  latter,  or  the  Cliurch,  has 
been  from  her  very  commencement  the  absolutely  universal 
community,  whereas  it  is  only  gradually  that  the  moral  com- 
munity, or  the  State,  becomes  the  all-embracing  community, 
and  that  instead  of  isolated  national  States,  there  arises  an 
organised  system  of  States,  forming  one  perfect  whole.  It  is 
self-evident  that  Rothe  does  not  hold  that  religion  will  dis- 
appear in  the  State,  but  regards  it  as  existing  in  its  highest 
form,  when  it  pervades  and  moulds  the  various  moral  spheres 
which,  while  maintaining  relative  independence,  are  all  em- 
braced by  the  State.  Accordingly,  lie  calls  his  perfect  State 
the  city  of  God,  a  theocracy  in  the  highest  sense  of  the  word, 
i.  p.  424.  He  holds  that  the  State  embraces  all  other  spheres, 
but  does  not  admit  the  converse  of  this.  Thus  they  are  no 
longer  co-ordinate  with  the  State.  With  this  fact  is  connected 
another,  viz.  that  Rothe  does  not  make  ricjlit  or  justice  alone 
the  prineiijle  of  the  State,  but  love  as  well.  Nay,  lie  even  says 
that  the  State  in  the  course  of  its  development  is  again  hecoming 
a  great  all- emhracing  family.  This  is  a  virtual  confession  that 
the  final  consummation  may  just  as  ivcll  be  described  as  a 
family  as  (by  Rothe)  a  State,  and  that  no  sufficient  grounds 
can  be  adduced,  why  the  State  should  be  singled  out  as 
absolutely  destined  to  be  the  sole  moral  community.  We 
might  quite  as  well  say,  that  the  State  will  cease  to  exist  as  a 
State,  that  is,  simply  as  an  institution  working  by  compulsory 
means  for  the  maintenance  of  right  (§§  33«,  34«).      But  the 


520  §  71.    SUMMARY. 

question,  whether  the  Cliurch  ivill  ever  cease  in  presence  of  the 
State,  depends  upon  another— whether  public  worship  can  be 
conceived  as  belonging  to  the  functions  of  the  State,  or  whether 
as  a  State  it  can  perform  acts  of  a  religious  nature.  Since  it 
cannot  do  this,  and  since,  nevertheless,  common  action  is 
necessary  for  this  purpose,  there  must  always  be  a  religious 
community,  and  it  will  in  its  own  way  include  the  State  no 
less  than  the  State  includes  it.  The  religious  community  must 
not  be  dissolved,  and  religion  exist  merely  in  the  piety  of  all 
individuals  belonging  to  the  State,  or  in  the  pious  character  ot 
the  other  spheres  of  life.  There  is  not  only  the  State,  science, 
and  art  desiring  on  their  own  parts  to  be  Christian  and  pious, 
nor  is  there  merely  a  piety  desiring  to  exist  so  far  as  it  can  be 
manifested  in  and  by  the  other  spheres  of  life,  as,  so  to  speak 
one  of  their  properties,  but  also  a  piety  of  a  social  kind 
desiring  to  exist  as  such,  and  there  is  therefore  also  a  com- 
munity desiring  to  exist  as  a  religious  community.  Eor  God 
does  not  exist  merely  in  the  multiplicity  of  the  world ;  He  is 
not  to  be  loved  merely  in  our  fellow-men,  but  also  in  Himself 
and  for  Himself  alone  (§  50).  The  right  of  religion  to  form  a 
community  of  its  own  could  only  be  contested  if  everything 
external,  everything  in  the  way  of  organization,  were  under  the 
control  of  the  State.  But  the  State  has  no  such  supreme 
power.  It  recognises  private  rights,  private  property,  and 
the  free  disposal  of  it,  although  it  can  interfere  in  cases  of 
necessity.  It  surrounds  everything  with  its  protection,  but 
does  not  meddle  with  every  petty  matter.  Most  things  are 
left  to  the  free  management  of  the  individual.  Nor  can  we 
suppose  that  even  in  the  final  consummation  only  the  S2^irit  of 
prayer  will  prevail  in  our  work,  and  that  no  special  times  will 
be  devoted  to  worship.  And  if  only  imUic  worship  be 
recognised  as  the  essential  function  of  the  religious  com- 
munity, it  cannot  be  said  that  the  Church  is  destined  to  be 
absorbed  in  the  State  ;  and  further,  the  Church  ^s'ill  have, 
during  the  whole  of  its  earthly  career,  a  spiritual  organization 
regulated  by  the  principle  of  worship.  Thus  there  will  always 
be  teachers  and  hearers,  order  of  worship  and  means  of 
worship,  doctrines  and  a  system  of  doctrine,  institutions  for  the 
education  of  teachers,  congregational  and  pastoral  organiza- 
tions, an  administration  department  and  a  constitution,  and 


MORAL  COMMUNITIES  TEANSITORY,  521 

these  give  rise  to  riglits  on  the  part  of  the   Church,  which  do 
not  come  under  the  rights  that  belong  to  the  State. 

2.  In  their  earthly  form,  all  these  communities  have  a 
transitory,  a  piedagogic  side.  Their  present  form  is  based  upon 
the  succession  of  new  generations,  and  the  pedagogic  relation 
which  the  one  portion  of  mankind  holds  to  the  other.  Thus 
marriage  and  the  family  will  cease  to  exist  on  their  natural 
side.  "  They  neither  marry  nor  are  given  in  marriage  "  (Matt, 
xxii.  30).  The  State,  too,  will  be  no  longer  recognisable  in  its 
earthly  shape  at  the  time  of  the  consummation.  Litigation 
and  lawsuits,  right  of  succession  and  penal  administration, 
separated  nationalities,  military,  finance,  and  police  will  all  be 
unknown.  Law  and  justice  will  no  longer  appear  severed  from 
each  other.  In  the  Church,  too,  catechetical  and  missionary 
activity  will  cease ;  there  will  be  no  need  of  professional 
teachers,  theological  faculties,  or  consistories.  On  the  other 
side,  however  (§  31),  it  must  also  be  said,  that  in  all  these 
communities  there  is  an  eternal  germ,  a  type  of  that  which 
the  consummation  will  usher  in ;  nay,  that  it  is  by  means  of 
these  communities  that  the  consummation  will  be  brought 
about.  Accordingly  our  Lord  has  taken  illustrations  of  His 
kingdom  from  them  all — from  marriage,  the  family,  the  city, 
the  community,  and  the  State  (Matt.  xvi.  18  ;  Eev.  xxi. ;  John 
iii.  29;  Matt.  ix.  15,  xxv.  1  f.).  In  the  notion  of  the 
Church,  that  temporal  side  which  belongs  to  the  conception  of 
the  perfected  community  is  certainly  not  so  happily  expressed 
as  in  the  word  State.  But  in  the  latter  expression,  again,  the 
ideal  side,  which  is  the  most  important  one,  is  less  prominent. 
Accordingly,  the  primitive  Christian  phrase  Kingdom  of  God 
is  to  be  preferred  (so  Schwarz  and  Hirscher).  But  the 
kingdom  is  not  a  thing  of  the  world  to  come  alone ;  neither 
is  it  the  invisible  Church  merely,  nor  does  it  consist  simply  in 
Christian  rules  of  life ;  it  is  something  that  has  actually 
begun  to  exist.  In  the  empirical  Christian  communities 
its  realization  has  commenced. 


522  §  72.  MAREIAGE. 

FIRST  SECTION 

THE  FUNDAMENTAL  MORAL  COMMUNITY,  OR  THE  HOUSEHOLD. 

CHAPTER  FIRST. 

MARRIAGE. 

The  Literature. — Liebetrut,  J.  Mueller,  Uehcr  Ehescheidung, 
etc.,  18o4.  Kircluntagsvortrarj.  Richter,  GcsrJiichte  der  Ehe- 
scheMung  in  d.  Evang.  Kirche.  Deutsche  ZeUschrift,  1858. 
Hofmann,  Theologische  Ethik,  p.  213  f.  Hofmanii,  Zcitschrift 
fur  Protestantismus  und  Kirche,  vol.  xxxvii.  [J.  G.  Fichte, 
Sgstem  der  Sittenlehre,  Wcrhe,  vol.  iv.  Hegel,  RccJitsphilosopliic. 
Schleiermacher,  Entiourf  eines  Systems  der  Sittenlehre.  Pre- 
digtcn  iiher  den  ehristlichen  Hausstand.  Christliche  Sitte.  Rothe, 
2nd  ed.  ii.  pp.  265-304.  Baumann,  Sechs  Vortrri'/e,  p.  23  f. 
Trendelenburg,  Naturrecht,  §  122  f.  Martensen,  Christian 
Ethics,  ii.  p.  7  ff.  v.  Scheurl,  Das  gemeine  deutsche  Eherecht 
nnd  seine  Umlildung,  1882.  Koehler,  TJeher  Trauung  vnid 
Trauformcn.  Zcitschrift  f.  prahtische  TheoL,  1879.  Harless, 
Die  Ehescheidungcfrage,  1861.  Cf.  also  his  System  of  Christian 
Ethics.  Sohin,  Das  Bccht  der  Eheschliessung .  Roedenbeck, 
Von  der  Ehc.  StudAcn  vnd  Kritiken,  1881,  also  published 
separately,  v.  Oettingen,  OUigatorische  und  fakidtatirc  Civilehe 
nach  dcm  Ergclnisse  der  Moralstatistik,  1881.  Thoenes,  Die 
christliche  Anschauung  von  der  Ehe.^ 

§72. 

Marriage  is  the  union  of  two  persons  of  opposite  sexes  in  the 
most  intimate  fellowship  of  body  and  soul,  a  fellowship 
in  which  each  personality  has  its  deficiencies  supplied, 
and  both  together  form  a  higher  unity.  It  is  the  sacred 
home,  both  physical  and  mental,  where  the  race  repro- 
duces itself  by  means  of  the  married  pair,  while  it  is  for 
the  latter  themselves  a  fuller  evolution  of  their  physical 
life.  Marriage  is  essentially  monogamic  and  indissoluble, 
and  only  as  such  can  it  be  morally  contracted.  The 
negative  condition  of  a  moral  union  is,  that  no  marriage 


SCPJPTUKAL  CONCEPTION  OF  MAP.PJAGE.  523 

be  contracted  with  a  person  with  whom,  whether  on 
physical,  psychical,  or  mental  grounds,  intimate  fellow- 
ship of  the  kind  described  would  be  impossible.  The 
jjositive  condition  is,  that  there  should  be  free  choice  and 
inward  inclination,  that  is,  that  the  two  persons  be  ready 
to  give  themselves  unreservedly  to  each  other,  and  also 
that  they  should  be  willing  to  join  the  great  moral  com- 
munities, and  this  they  do  when  marriage  is  regarded  as 
a  civil  and  religious  contract. 

1.  Scri'ptural  conception  of  Mcirria/jc.  Gen.  ii.  2-1,  although 
written  in  an  age  of  polygamy,  advances  so  high  and  pure  a 
conception  of  marriage,  that  Christ  goes  back  to,  and  adopts 
it  (Matt.  xi.v.  4  f.).  Let  the  husband,  in  the  East  the  lord, 
follow  the  impulse  of  love  to  his  wife,  which  is  stronger  than 
filial  love,  that  he  may  become  one  flesh,  one  being  with  her. 
When  the  two  become  one,  a  union  of  closest  intimacy  is 
formed,  involving  also  a  co-ordination.  But  this  first  state 
was  followed  by  the  fall,  and  with  it  the  will  of  the  woman 
was  made  subject  to  the  man  ;  his  authority  and  her  obedience 
were,  on  the  ground  of  natural  difference  in  point  of  strength, 
made  harshly  prominent,  M'ith  the  view,  however,  of  insuring 
unity,  a  final  decision  in  matters  of  dispute,  and  the  welfare 
of  the  family.  Gentleness  and  prudence  may  ameliorate  the 
condition  of  the  woman.  The  relations  between  husband  and 
wife  were  not  essentially  altered  before  the  time  of  Christ ; 
on  the  contraiy,  polygamy  intervened,  and  was  not  forbidden 
by  the  law ;  and  if  in  the  time  of  Christ  intercourse  with 
nations  that  practised  monogamy  had  made  polygamy  less 
common,  yet,  on  the  other  hand,  divorce  was  made  all  the  more 
easy,  and  hence  what  may  be  called  successive  polygamy  in- 
creased. Christ  first  of  all  re-establishes  the  manner  in  which 
marriage  was  observed  at  the  beginning.  Matt.  xix.  3-9  ; 
Mark  x.  2-12  ;  Luke  xvi.  18,  declares  against  divorce  as 
involving  sin  on  the  side  of  the  guilty  party,  and  again 
enforces  the  objective  sanctity  and  perpetual  obligation  of 
marriage.  Every  separation  presupposes  sin.  Whom  God 
hath  joined  together,  no  man  may  put  asunder.  Xo  human 
i'orm  of  divorce  is  higher  than  the  primitive  rigkts  of  marriage. 


524  §  72.   MAREIAGE. 

These,  on  tlie  contrary,  stand  permanently  opposed  to  the 
subjective  caprice  that  would  sever  the  marriage  union,  oblige 
those  who  have  already  broken  it  to  restore  it,  and  make  it  a 
sin  to  contract  a  new  marriage,  when  the  first  has  been 
sinfully  dissolved  (Matt.  v.  31  f.).  Neither  Luke  nor  Mark 
mentions  iropveia  as  a  ground  of  separation.  But  the  omission 
explains  itself,  inasmuch  as  marriage  is  at  once  broken  by 
TTopveia,  as  the  word  itself  implies.  In  the  New  Testament 
the  matter  is  viewed,  not  from  the  standpoint  of  one  of  the 
married  parties,  but  from  that  of  the  unity  of  the  objective 
relation ;  morally  speaking,  that  relation  admits  of  absolutely 
no  dissolution ;  only  sin  and  crime  can  sever  it  (1  Cor.  vii. 
10).  So  high  is  the  position  assigned  to  the  universal  moral 
rights  of  marriage,  that  even  when  a  Christian  is  united  to 
an  unbeliever,  the  marriage  tie  must  still  subsist,  if  the  non- 
Christian  partner  wishes  it ;  if  not,  then  the  Christian  is  free. 
The  Pastoral  Epistles  (Tit.  i.  6 ;  1  Tim.  iii.  2)  disapprove  of 
choosing  Church  officials  from  among  those  who  are  practising 
successive  i^olygamy, — probably  for  the  sake  of  good  report. 
For  according  to  1  Cor.  vii.  39,  those  who  have  been  widowed 
are  permitted  to  marry  again.  The  suhordination  of  the  wife 
is  often  insisted  on  by  the  apostle :  not  as  if  the  state  of 
things  brought  about  by  the  fall  were  always  to  remain  the 
same,  even  among  Christians  (Eph.  v.  23  f.),  but  because  that 
difference  between  governing  and  obeying,  which  has  its 
foundation  in  a  benevolent  natural  ordinance,  has  no  other 
claim  than  to  result  in  a  love  which  recognises  this  divinely- 
ordained  difference.  And  this  point  of  view,  when  adopted 
by  the  woman,  is  the  surest  means  of  gaining  ascendancy 
over  the  man,  and  inducing  his  love  to  raise  her  to  co-ordina- 
tion with  himself.  It  is  in  entire  harmony,  too,  with  the 
natural  position  of  the  husband,  that  the  co-ordination  should 
proceed  from  him.  He  must  not  resign  his  place  as  the 
head;  it  is  not  only  his  right,  but  above  all  his  duty  to 
maintain  it,  and  it  would  be  prejudicial  to  married  and 
family  life  for  him  to  become  the  one  who  is  ruled.  But 
that  with  this  subordination  of  the  wife  to  the  husband 
there  may  nevertheless  be  a  free  relation  of  love  between 
them,  based  on  the  difference  of  the  sexes,  is  seen  from  the 
fact,  that  marriage  has  been   honoured   by   being   called   an 


IIISTOKY  OF  THE  CHRISTIAN  IDEA  OF  MARRIAGE.  525 

emblem  of  the  relation  of  Christ  to  the  Church  (Eph.  v.  23- 
33  ;  cf.  Col.  iii.  18  ;  Heb.  xiii.  4).  To  prohibit  marriage  is 
characterized  as  demoniacal,  as  enmity  towards  God,  the 
Creator. 

2.  History  of  Ideas  regarding  Marriage  in  Christian  Times. 
At  first  the  Old  Testament  spirit  prevailed  in  Christendom, 
and  the  personality  of  the  wife,  as  well  as  of  the  children,  was 
thrust  into  the  background.  Still  there  was  not  wanting  the 
consciousness  of  essential  equality,  to  which  all  are  raised  by 
baptism.  The  sanctity  of  marriage  was  very  highly  esteemed 
among  Christians ;  they  adhered  to  monogamy  and  the  in- 
dissolubility of  the  marriage  tie,  and  many  of  them  did  so, 
not  only  with  regard  to  the  present  world,  but  also  with 
regard  to  the  next,  by  looking  upon  a  second  marriage  after 
the  death  of  a  first  husband  as  conjugal  infidelity,  the  disrup- 
tion of  a  bond  still  in  existence.  According  to  Athenagoras, 
second  marriage  is  evTrpeTrrj^i  iropveia.  The  Montanists, 
especially  Tertullian,^  held  the  same  view  still  more  decidedly, 
maintaining  that  a  second  marriage  was  fornication.  Marriage 
was  conceived  from  a  religious  point  of  view,  and  accordingly 
the  Church  soon  began  to  take  part  in  the  contraction  of  it. 
The  first  traces  of  this  are  to  be  found  in  the  Ignatian  Epistles, 
according  to  which  marriage  ought  not  to  take  place  without 
the  knowledge  of  the  bishop — the  purpose  being  to  restrain 
Christians  from  mixed  marriages.  Both  in  unmarried  and 
married  life  the  strictest  chastity  was  demanded,  and  was 
universally  practised  in  the  earliest  Christian  ages,  so  that 
the  coarse  reproach  of  /litfei?  could  be  met  by  Athenagoras^  by 
saying,  that  Christians,  on  the  contrary,  believed  that  virginity 
and  complete  continence  bring  us  nearer  to  God  {fiaWov 
iraplaTTjcn  dew).  Here,  indeed,  is  the  point  at  which  the 
lack  of  a  developed  Christian  anthropology,  and  especially  of 
a  Christian  doctrine  of  the  relation  between  body  and  spirit, 
becomes  apparent.  The  consequence  of  this  want  was,  that  a 
still  surviving  remnant  of  dualism  broke  out,  and  found 
adherents  on  one  hand  in  the  Gnostics,  on  the  other  in  the 

•  De  monogamia — written  before  he  became  a  Montanist — and  tie  exliortatione 
castigatis.  Cf.  Hauber,  TertiiUiarCfi  Kampf  gcgen  die  zioeite  Ehe.  Studienund 
Kritiken,  1845,  H.  3. 

■  C.  33. 


526  §  72.   MAEFJAGE. 

Manichaeans.  And  its  spread  was  also  favoured  by  the  fact, 
that  the  position  which  the  first  Christians  were  compelled 
to  assume  toward  heathenism  was  very  apt  to  become 
negative  and  one-sided.  The  apostolic  Fathers  and  the 
apologists  do  indeed  recognise  marriage  as  an  ordinance  of 
God.  But  part  of  them  hold  that  it  is  a  still  higher  virtue  ^ 
to  remain  unmarried  altogether,  or  at  least  to  practise  con- 
tinence in  the  conjugal  relation.  Here  (as  in  their  attitude  to 
the  State)  there  already  lay  the  germs  of  that  which  was 
afterwards  reduced  to  a  system  in  monasticism.  As  far  as 
the  family  is  concerned,  the  most  important  thing  to  be 
noticed  is,  that  the  high  conception,  which  Christianity 
introduced,  of  the  worth  of  personality  could  not  but  improve 
the  condition  of  children,  with  regard  both  to  their  education 
and  the  moral  value  attached  to  them.  In  all  probability, 
however,  infant  baptism,  in  which  this  higher  conception 
receives  the  seal  of  the  Church,  did  not  become  a  dogma  aud 
prevailing  custom  until  after  the  apostolic  age,  and  was  in 
Tertullian's  time  still  a  matter  of  dispute.  He  blames  the 
practice  of  bringing  innocent  children  to  be  baptized.  Among 
the  Germanic  nations,  woman  was  held  in  high  respect  even 
before  the  introduction  of  Christianity ;  nevertheless  in  the 
rude  ages  that  preceded  it,  the  custom  of  having  concubines 
existed,  and  was  not  infrequently  practised  by  their  chiefs. 
It  was  Christianity  that  first  actually  established  monogamy 
among  them.  The  chivalrous  love  of  the  Middle  Ages  saw  in 
the  woman  the  ideal  of  the  genuinely  human — which  was 
personified  in  the  Virgin  Mary.  In  the  Middle  Ages,  the 
chastity  of  the  man,  where  it  is  not — as  in  monasticism — of 
a  negative  kind,  consists  mainly  in  chivalrousness,  which 
makes  him  protect  the  honour  of  woman,  not  only  against 
others,  but  also  against  himself.  Spain  did  not  get  beyond 
this  point.  Yet  this  romanticism  applied  more  to  woman  in 
abstrado,  to  the  womanly ;  marriage  itself  was  not  essentially 
altered  by  it,  more  especially  as  celibacy,  with  its  spirtualistic 
ethics,   designated    marriage   as   an   imperfect    state,  nay,   as 

'  Tert.  adv.  Marc.  Marriage  is  indeed  a  work  of  God,  but  there  is  neverthe- 
less a  stain  of  desire  adhering  to  it.  As  a  chiliast  he  further  believed  that  all 
marriages  would  soon  be  superfluous.  With  Origen,  too,  marriage  occupies  a 
lower  place  than  celibacy.     The  Holy  Spirit  cannot  be  present  in  generat'io. 


AT  THE  REFOKMATION,  527 

belonging  merely  to  the  sphere  of  things  allowable ;  and  in 
consequence  of  this  men  partially  lost  sight  of  the  moral 
duty  of  bringing  married  life  under  the  permeating  power  of 
the  Christian  spirit.  Thus  the  ethics  of  marriage  were 
developed  more  on  the  external  side,  by  restrictions  against 
divorce,  and  against  marriage  within  forbidden  degrees  of 
relationship.  The  permanent  obligation  of  marriage  was 
based  upon  its  sacramental  form,  and  the  forbidden  degrees 
were  defined  by  positive  statutes. 

At  the  Reformation  two  results  ensued.  On  the  one  side, 
the  unnaturalness  of  this  view  of  marriage  was  exposed, 
particularly  by  Luther  and  the  other  Keformers ;  nature 
received  her  rights,  and  marriage  was  recognised  as  a  divine 
institution,  in  connection  with  the  principle,  that  the  whole  of 
liuman  life  is  capable  of  being,  and  is  meant  to  be,  pervaded  by 
the  moral  influence  of  the  Holy  Ilvevfia.  Other  limitations 
were  abolished,  such  as  the  unwarrantable  extension  of  pro- 
Idbitions  against  marriage  on  account  of  ties  of  relationship. 
Marriage  was  also  deprived  of  its  sacramental  significance,  but 
at  the  same  time  its  ethical  dignity  as  a  divine  institution  was 
vindicated.  Hence  it  followed,  that,  like  all  ethical  blessings, 
it  could  be  ruined  and  destroyed  by  sin,  that  divorce  therefore 
might  be  rendered  necessary  by  human  guilt,  and  that  it  was 
no  part  of  the  duty  of  Church  or  State  to  uphold  a  semblance 
of  marriage,  when  marriage  itself  no  longer  existed.  On  the 
other  side,  however,  the  time  of  the  Eeformation  exhibits  a 
resemblance  to  the  romanticism  of  the  Middle  Ages ;  for  in 
the  woman  it  sees  the  species,  so  that  for  this  age,  too,  one 
woman  is  very  much  the  same  as  another.  Friends  procured 
wives  for  each  other,  as  in  the  case  of  Melanchthon  and 
Calvin.  The  act  of  personal  choice,  preference  for  the 
individual  as  such,  were  but  little  regarded ;  and  this  held 
good  not  only  for  the  woman,  but  also  for  the  man.  Even  his 
own  individual  sympathies  were  regarded  by  the  latter  as  not 
of  very  much  importance.  Here,  indeed,  there  was  something 
great ;  viz.  that  men  looked  to  the  objective  authority  and 
sanctity  of  the  marriage  relation,  to  its  objective  right  and 
inorality.  Still,  individuality  was  too  little  recognised, 
although  it  received  in  other  respects  such  a  powerful  stimulus 
from  the  Eeformation.      The  claims  of  religious  personality 


528  §  "2.    MARRIAGE. 

were  acknowledged,  but  only  as  essentially  the  same  in  all ; 
men  were  not  as  yet  fully  conscious  that  in  marriage  ethical 
individuality  had  a  rightful  part  to  play.  So  matters  stood 
until  the  close  of  the  l7th  century.  From  the  time  of 
the  18th  century,  again,  the  personal  and  individual  side 
has  been  the  more  strongly  emphasized,  nay,  so  brought  into 
the  foreground,  as  if  all  that  is  divine  in  the  marriage  relation 
were  to  be  found  here  alone,  and  not  in  that  relation  itself 
as  an  objective  ethical  ordinance.  Fiction,  too,  has  con- 
tributed its  share  towards  completely  ruining  the  representa- 
tion of  marriage  as  a  divine  institution  of  objective  validity, 
and  making  it  nothing  more  than  a  subjective  product,  a 
matter  of  mere  sympathy,  of  desire  and  inclination.  Even 
Kant,  earnest  as  he  was,  conceived  it  simply  as  a  matter  of 
subjective  contract.  But  with  such  views  as  these,  the  indis- 
solubility of  marriage  cannot  be  maiiiLained.  For,  if  every- 
thing were  to  be  decided  by  individuality,  then  should  the 
elective  affinities  and  sympathies  of  two  married  couples  cross 
each  other,  the  objective  institution  would  at  the  most  receive 
only  outward  respect,  and  that  for  the  sake  of  propriety. 
Further,  passionate,  natural  love  would  obtain  a  false  ascend- 
ancy, an  apotheosis  to  which  it  has  absolutely  no  right  [as  in 
fiction].  By  such  an  evidently  enhanced  requirement  of  love 
for  marriage,  if  it  is  to  be  marriage,  indeed,  its  tie  would  be 
absolutely  loosened,  since  it  would  thus  be  made  to  depend 
upon  empirical  and  individual  considerations.  Worthless 
novels  have  in  many  ways  had  a  pernicious  effect  upon  our 
ideas  concerning  marriage  by  making  it  an  aftair  of  mere 
sympathy.  But  the  worst  effect  is  produced  by  that  false  and 
delusive  notion  of  marriage,  according  to  which  a  person 
should  expect  to  obtain  from  marriage — if  it  is  to  be  a  valid 
one — such  full  satisfaction  on  the  individual  side  of  his 
nature,  that  he  and  his  partner,  finding  in  each  other  whatever 
they  need  in  this  respect,  will  have  no  want  unsupplied. 
Here  each  of  the  two  expects  everything  from  the  other,  "  to 
be  made  happy "  in  a  eudoemonistic  fashion.  But  virtuous 
happiness  must  be  more  deeply  rooted  than  this.  And  so, 
when  husband  and  wife  do  not  find  all  they  looked  for,  their 
married  life  becomes  unhappy,  they  think  there  is  no  longer 
any  reason  to  continue  it,  and  that  separation  is  allowable. 


MAKEIAGE.  529 

With  us,  the  Legislature  has  shown  a  reprehensible  compliance 
with  this  subjectivism,  by  granting  divorce  on  account  of 
"invincible  dislike!'  But  wherever  divorce  is  easily  obtained, 
the  reaction  is  felt  upon  married  life,  upon  education,  and 
upon  the  welfare  of  the  whole  people.  For  many  a  marriage 
that  has  begun  badly  has  turned  out  well,  when  husband  and 
wife  have  been  impelled  by  the  consciousness  that  separation 
is  impossible,  to  struggle  against  hardness  of  heart,  to  take 
pains  with  themselves  and  attain  to  self-control,  and  thus  to 
amend  a  state  of  matters  that  at  first  was  perhaps  no  more 
than  endurable. 

According  to  Socialistic  and  Communistic  theories,  so  far  as 
they  deal  with  marriage  and  the  family,  marriage  is  to  cease 
to  exist  as  a  separate  association  formed  by  two  persons,  and 
meant  to  be  lasting  and  exclusive.  If  ever  these  theories 
could  be  carried  into  effect,  they  would  result  in  the  degrada- 
tion of  the  woman  most  of  all,  but  also  of  the  man  as  well. 
]\Ien  would,  as  in  imperial  times,  no  longer  care  to  form  indis- 
soluble ties,  but  prefer  their  own  wandering  fancy — the  Venus 
rag  a. 

A  departure  from  this  subjectivism  was  initiated  by  the 
philosophy  of  Schelling  and  Hegel,  in  so  far  as  it  fixed  its 
attention  not  upon  the  will,  not  upon  happiness,  but  upon 
external  objective  being  as  the  expression  of  pure  will,  and  so 
brought  men  back  to  the  recognition  of  objective  authorities ; 
cf  in  particular  Hegel's  BecJitsphilosophie.  But  it  is  Schleier- 
macher  especially,  who,  while  at  the  same  time  giving  full 
consideration  to  the  claims  of  individuality,  has  indicated  the 
objective  character  of  marriage,  and  made  prominent  its 
fundamental  importance  for  all  moral  communities. 

When  we  look  at  the  development  of  ideas  regarding 
marriage,  especially  in  our  own  day,  and  at  the  numerous 
divorces  connected  with  them,  especially  in  those  regions 
where  Prussian  statute-law  is  in  force,  we  see  plainly,  that 
what  our  age  stands  most  in  need  of,  is  that  the  objective 
character  of  marriage  should  be  rescued  from  that  subjective 
caprice  which,  under  the  form  of  individual  likes  or  dislikes, 
is  exerting  such  widespread  influence.  Of  course  we  must  at 
the  same  time  never  neglect  consideration  of  the  individual 
side    of  the   matter.      The   people   at    large   must    again   be 

2  L 


530  §  72.    MARRIAGE. 

brought  to  recognise  in  marriage  an  objective,  sacred  power 
and  institution,  which  demands,  indeed,  free  consent  on  the 
part  of  those  whom  it  unites,  but  can  never  be  legitimately 
dissolved  on  account  of  individual  likes  and  dislikes.  Only 
on  this  objective  basis  is  a  true  marriage  possible ;  and  such  a 
marriage  will  also  be  in  a  condition  to  bring  about,  in  an 
ethical  way,  an  ever-increasing  harmony  and  understanding 
between  husband  and  wife,  and  to  yield  the  blessing  that  God 
has  placed  in  it  to  those  who  seek  it.  Mere  empirical 
individuality  of  character,  so  far  as  it  is  not  in  conformity 
with  God's  will,  has  no  right  to  be  the  cause  of  breaking 
the  marriage  bond ;  and,  on  the  other  hand,  individuality 
in  conformity  with  the  will  of  God,  so  far  as  it  has  become 
empiric,  in  other  words,  has  been  realized,  can  never  be  morally 
repulsive ;  with  it  the  formation  of  an  intimate  moral  alliance 
must  always  be  possible.  Hence  in  the  case  of  husband  and 
wife  whose  individualities  in  their  natural  state  are  not  at 
first  very  favourable  to  their  union,  the  only  thing  required 
is,  that  they  should  cleanse  the  pure  metal  from  the  dross. 
And  thus  marriage  will  be  for  each,  as  it  ought  to  be,  a 
strengthening  and  purifying  of  their  personal  characters. 
Neither  of  them  is  without  faults ;  but  if  they  are  Christians, 
the  faults  of  the  one  will  bring  forth  and  exercise  just 
the  opposite  virtues  in  the  other,  and  by  this  means  they 
will  become  more  and  more  able  to  assist  each  other  in  over- 
coming these  faults,  and  to  make  their  union  and  happiness 
more  complete. 

3.  "When  marriage  is  defined  as  indissoluble,  a  union — 
which  State  and  Church  must  recognise — of  two  persons  of 
opposite  sexes  in  the  most  intimate  fellowship  of  body  and 
soul,  a  fellowship  in  which  each  personahty  has  its  deficiencies 
supplied  by  the  other,  this  definition  contains  both  the 
objective  side  of  marriage,  or  marriage  as  an  institution,  and 
its  subjective  side  of  affection.  Moreover,  it  is  clear  from  this 
definition  that,  on  the  one  side,  there  were  real  marriages 
before  the  time  of  Christ  (of.  supra,  p.  305),  and  therefore  that 
it  is  not  the  sacrament  of  the  Church  which  makes  marriage 
what  it  is ;  while,  on  the  other,  it  is  no  less  clear  that  marriage 
in  its  perfect  form  cannot  be  thought  of  apart  from  Christianity, 
since  marriage  exists  between  persons,  and  it  is  from  Chris- 


THE  PHYSICAL  SIDE.  531 

tiaiiity  that  persons  derive  the  principle  of  perfection.  As  we 
have  already  seen  (§  1 7),  the  mere  physical  side  of  the  union 
would  not  of  itself  constitute  marriage,  but  only  sexual  fellow- 
ship. But  just  as  distinctly — and  in  a  certain  sense  even 
more  distinctly — must  the  fact  be  emphasized,  that  neither 
can  psychical  affinity,  or  the  spiritual  side,  be  of  itself 
taken  as  its  basis.  The  spiritual  side  would  of  itself  do  no 
m.ore  than  create  quite  another  relation,  that  of  friendship ; 
and  it  would  be  immoral  to  confuse  different  spheres,  and 
build  up  marriage  upon  friendship  alone.  If  marriage  is  to 
be  distinct  from  every  other  moral  community,  its  essential 
character  must  be  conditioned  by  the  natural  side,  but 
constituted  by  the  union  of  the  phj'sical  and  the  spiritual. 
For  that  is  the  form  which  human  sex  life  must  assume,  and 
marriage  has  its  basis  in  the  category  of  life — (cohabitation) 
— but  a  life  that  is  human,  in  which  it  is  personality  and  not 
iTTLdvfjbia  that  must  govern.  It  is  the  duty  of  man  as  a 
j)ersonal  being  to  keep  the  natural  in  subjection,  since  it  exists 
for  the  spiritual,  not  the  spiritual  for  it.  Marriage,  con- 
sidered in  itself,  exhibits  a  completion  of  human  nature  in  the 
aspect  in  which  it  has  differentiated  itself  in  the  two  sexes ; 
in  it,  in  accordance  with  God's  will,  the  differences  both 
physical  and  spiritual,  that  exist  between  the  sexes,  are 
gathered  up  into  unity  in  the  way  of  moral  action.  Mere 
TCKvoTroua  does  not  denote  the  aim  of  marriage.  This  depends 
upon  the  blessing  of  God.  Neither  does  marriage  exist 
merely  as  a  precaution  against  incontinentia.  Just  as  little 
is  its  object  simply  the  attainment  of  married  happiness,  how- 
ever certain  it  may  be  that  marriage  is  able  to  afford  the 
highest  earthly  felicity.  But  it  is  a  state  appointed  by  God, 
a  K\rj(TL<i  (1  Cor.  vii.),  because  here  an  ethical  design  planned 
hi/  nature  is  raised  out  of  possibility  into  actuality.  In 
marriage  two  duties  are  performed  and  stand  in  the  most 
intimate  union  with  each  other,  duty  to  oneself  and  duty  to 
one's  neighbour — the  latter  being  in  the  present  instance  the 
husband  or  wife. 

The  physical  side  of  marriage,  the  bodily  cohabitation  of 
husband  and  wife,  is  the  external  hasis  of  the  relation,  the 
conditio  sine  qua  non  of  the  realization  of  this  moral  associa- 
tion.     But,  at  the  same  time,  it  must  bo  the  basis  for  some- 


532  §  72.    MARRIAGE. 

thing  else,  and  not  be  mere  iropveia.  For  tliose  who  are 
joined  together  in  body  are  human  heings ;  and  therefore  their 
physical  connection  must  exist  for  the  purpose  of  rendering 
possible  an  inward  spiritual  union  —  nay,  it  must  be  the 
beginning  of  such  a  union.  The  external  basis  is  not  the  aim 
of  marriage,  but  what  makes  a  true  marriage  possible.  It  is 
also  a  necessary  condition  of  the  realization  of  marriage,  that 
the  spiritual  side  of  the  relation  should  not  be  wanting,  but 
should  be  present  as  a  beginning,  though  an  imperfect  one  ; 
more  and  more  perfect  spiritual  union  being  the  ultimate  goal 
itself.  It  is  for  this  reason  that  Christianity  is  so  important 
for  marriage.  It  did  not  indeed  first  exist  through  Christianity ; 
but  the  latter  alone  brings  marriage  into  full  conformity  with 
its  idea ;  for  the  redemptive  power  that  is  in  it  restrains  and 
eradicates  whatever  would  cause  discord,  increases  the  love  of 
the  married  pair,  and  enhances  their  value  in  each  other's 
eyes,  as  partakers  of  the  same  hope.  It  should  be  required 
of  Christian  marriage  that  it  should  not  be  at  its  best  at  the 
beginning,  in  the  honeymoon,  in  the  days  of  early  passion, 
but  should  be  a  fellowship  that  becomes  closer  the  longer 
it  lasts. 

I'here  is  no  school  of  virtue  like  marriage,  none  so  well 
fitted  both  to  purify  and  strengthen  the  character  by  means 
of  the  joy  it  affords,  as  well  as  the  never-failing  suffering  it 
brings.  Upon  a  physical  foundation,  which  spiritualism 
despises  or  finds  repulsive,  God  has  built  up  an  association  of 
the  tenderest  kind,  embracing  the  highest  spiritual  relations, 
and  has  made  it  a  real  union  of  souls.  The  effect  of  the 
physical  side  of  marriage  is  that  this  relation  does  not,  like 
friendship,  consist  in  a  mere  series  of  intermittent  acts ;  on 
the  contrary,  although  its  subsistence  depends  upon  ethical 
activity,  it  is  nevertheless  a  continuous  state,  and  carries  in 
itself  a  sort  of  natural  security,  which  affords  a  basis  for  the 
feeling  of  home  in  man.  For  here  everything  is  common, 
property,  energy,  enjoyment,  body,  life,  joy  and  sorrow ;  and 
yet  this  relation  bears  a  personal  form.  For  not  only  is  each 
spouse  a  distinct  personality,  and  must  continue  to  be  so ;  in 
addition  to  this,  their  individual  wills  unite  to  form  one 
common  will,  which  makes  nature  subservient  to  the  welfare 
of  each,  and  promotes  their  moral  growth.      In   this  loving 


A  SCHOOL  OF  VIRTUE.  533 

devotion  of  husband  and  wife  to  each  other,  however  unre- 
served it  may  be,  no  loss  of  ])ersonality  is  involved,  but,  on  the 
contrary,  a  recovery  thereof  in  a  higher  sense.  A  new  and 
liigher  form  of  existence  is  attained  by  means  of  marriage. 
The  creation  w'as  not  perfected  when  Adam  was  made ;  he 
knew  that  he  was  as  yet  imperfect,  that  he  needed  completion 
— until  the  woman  was  given  to  him,  and  then  for  the  first 
time  he  knew  that  he  was  a  complete  unity.  At  the  same 
time,  marriage  is  hy  oio  means  a.  mere  expansion  of  the  individual 
ago :  for  if  it  were  so,  the  result  might  be  mere  selfishness, 
tlie  desire  to  absorb  another  in  oneself  On  the  contrary,  the 
personality  of  each  spouse  is  expanded  and  completed  in  the 
following  way.  Each  surrenders  himself  freely  to  the  other 
in  love,  to  be  the  means  of  amplifying  and  completing  the 
personality  of  the  other,  while  he  also  surrenders  himself  no 
less  freely  to  receive  the  same  service  that  he  renders.  And 
since  this  takes  place  on  both  sides,  the  higher  life  that 
results  is  shared  by  both  in  common.  Each,  to  whom  the 
person  of  the  other  is  freely  surrendered  in  love  to  be  the 
means  of  subserving  his  well-being,  has  tlie  assurance  that  he 
is  the  chosen  end  of  that  other.  The  former  also  does  the 
same.  And  thus  each  remains  by  means  of  the  other  an  end 
to  himself,  while  each  at  the  same  time  feels  and  exercises  a 
loving  self-forgetfulness — a  forgetfulness  in  which  love  is  not 
forgotten.  It  produces  a  peculiar  elevation  of  consciousness 
to  know  that  we  are  loved  by  a  person  faithfully,  truly,  and 
for  ever.  In  marriage,  too,  we  learn,  with  regard  to  earthly 
relations,  the  same  truth  that  the  Christian  is  taught  by 
religion,  viz.  that  in  the  long  run  there  is  no  true  blessing  but 
love,  both  that  which  is  received  and  that  which  is  conferred. 
Thus  marriage  is  the  school,  the  laboratory  of  true  love,  and 
thus,  too,  of  the  highest  earthly  bliss,  which  must  ever  be 
rooted  in  virtue.  Outwardly  a  Christian  husband  and  wife 
are  one.  No  sound  of  serious  discord  becomes  audible.  And 
since  they  thus  form  as  it  were  one  higher  person,  their  sense 
of  responsibility  is  increased,  while  they  also  feel  that  they 
are  living  a  richer  life.  The  care  of  each  for  himself  is 
always  elevated  into  care  for  the  other  as  well ;  they  have  all 
things  in  common.  Inwardly,  it  is  true,  husband  and  wife 
remain  two  independent  persons ;    but  they  are  not  simply 


534  §  72.    MARRIAGE. 

two  distinct  persons,  and  nothing  more,  for  each  of  them  has 
made  the  other  a  part  of  his  own  being ;  there  are  two  foci, 
but  one  ellipse.  It  shows  the  wonderful  objective  power  of 
this  relation,  that  here,  on  the  one  hand,  it  is  never  long  before 
egoism  betrays  itself  to  be  nothing  but  folly,  and  the  blows 
of  unfaithfulness  fall  upon  its  own  head.  On  tlie  other  hand, 
it  is  a  connection  of  such  tenderness  and  intimacy,  that  it  can 
never  prosper  nor  unfold  its  loveliness  and  charms,  where  the 
care  of  one  spouse  for  the  other  arises  from  egoism  and 
prudence  alone,  and  that  only  when  the  one  really  makes  the 
other  the  objective  aim  of  his  love,  does  self-renunciation 
meet  its  reward.  In  true  marriage,  liusband  and  wife  make 
it  their  aim  to  allow  nothing  to  come  between  them ;  they 
seek  by  oioen  confidence  to  be  perfectly  transparent  to  each 
other,  and  in  this  mutual  confidence  they  both  feel  that  they 
possess  the  surest  safeguard  of  their  married  happiness.  Still, 
here,  too  (§§  56,  69),  it  is  the  ideal  ego  that  they  must  love 
in  each  other,  the  empirical  ego  must  be  loved  only  so  far  as 
it  does  not  conflict  with  the  ideal.  Their  union  is  spiritual 
and  Christian,  only  so  long  as  they  promote  each  other's 
religious  and  moral  life. 

TIlc  failings  of  one  spouse  must  he  home  in  sympathy  hy  the 
other,  and  felt  as  his  own,  as  something  for  which  he  too  is 
responsible,  and  wmich  he  must  help  to  combat.  People  take 
things  easy  in  marriage,  and  let  their  faults  appear  as  readily 
as  their  virtues.  But  a  higher  conception  of  marriage  teaches 
the  duty  of  self-control,  and  that  only  what  is  best  and  noblest 
in  character  should  be  displayed.  Here,  as  well  as  elsewhere, 
respect  is  the  basis  of  love  and  its  duration.  Husband  and 
wife,  moreover,  have  a  peculiar  power  over  each  other,  arising 
from  the  constancy  of  their  mutual  influence.  From  the 
intimacy  of  the  matrimonial  relation,  both  of  them  become 
aware  of  each  other's  faults ;  but  marriage  is  a  school  of 
patience  and  gentleness,  and  affords  the  most  abundant  means 
for  self-discipline  and  self-knowledge.  And  if  husband  and 
wife  only  conduct  their  married  life  in  the  name  of  Christ, 
neither  their  union  nor  their  happiness  will  be  injured  by  sin, 
for  then  sin  is  contrary  to  their  will,  and  they  will  strive 
against  it  in  common,  and  above  all  by  their  common  prayer. 
Their   common  subordination  to   God  also  purifies   their  love 


CONTRACTION  OF  MAKEIAGE.  535 

from  sensual  passion,  "E^€lv  <^jvvalKa  a)9  /a^?  '^X^^  (-^  ^''-'^'• 
vii.  29).  Thus  tlieir  love  becomes  pure  and  strong,  and  this 
it  could  never  be  but  for  their  common  devotion  to  the 
Kedeemer, 

As  everytliing  is  held  in  common  in  Christian  marriage, 
and  the  marriage  bond  is  strengthened  thereby,  so  do  children 
in  particular,  who  are  the  fruit  of  mutual  love,  and  the 
blessing  which  God  has  attached  to  it,  contribute  to  such 
strengthening.  For  in  their  children  each  parent  sees  a 
continuation  as  it  were  of  the  personality  of  the  other,  and 
loves  the  other  in  them,  the  child  being  a  transcript,  not  of 
the  one  parent  only,  but  of  both. 

And,  finally,  husband  and  wife  must  also  devote  themselves 
to  some  moral  aim  lying  beyond  the  immediate  circle  of 
married  life.  For  when  they  are  entirely  wrapped  up  in 
each  other,  their  marriage  cannot  remain  a  healthy  one.  The 
more  exclusive  and  the  more  intense  their  wedded  love  is, 
the  more  necessary  is  it  that  they  should  look  beyond  the 
domestic  sphere.  It  is  only  when  they  thus  take  a  common 
interest  in  moral  aims,  that  their  married  life  reaches  full 
development  and  strength. 

4.  Conti'adion  of  Mar  day  c.  (a)  On  the  duty  in  general  of 
contracting  marriage.  Marriage  is,  apart  from  certain  special 
exceptions,  a  universal  calling,  natural  to  every  human  being ; 
a  calling  in  wliich  the  whole  community,  with  its  universal 
aims,  is  as  much  interested  as  the  individual  with  his  single 
and  particular  ones.  Evangelical  ethics,  following  the  New 
Testament,  starts  with  the  principle  that  to  enter  into  wedlock 
must  be  regarded  as  a  universal  calling  and  duty,  that  it  is 
not  a  matter  of  mere  choice  whether  one  will  do  so  or  not, 
and  that  special  grounds  must  exist  to  justify  an  exception  to 
the  rule,  and  to  prove  that  it  is  the  duty  of  this  person  or 
that  to  remain  unmarried.  Such  an  exception  may  arise  from 
external  causes,  e.g.  from  the  want  of  those  outward  means 
which  are  necessary  to  the  moral  establishment  of  a  house- 
liold.  Accordingly,  the  State  may  impose  restrictions  upon 
marriage.  Then,  too,  the  woman  must  wait  to  see  whether 
she  will  be  asked  in  marriage  by  a  man  whom  she  can  con- 
scientiously obey,  and  for  whom  she  has  an  affection.  Physical 
causes,  likewise,  such  as  bodily  infirmity,  may  form  a  moral 


536  §  72.    MARRIAGE. 

ground  for  not  marrying.  The  man  also  may  be  unable  to 
find  a  woman  to  whom  he  is  drawn  by  affection  ;  or  it  may 
be  that  while  there  is  liking  on  his  side,  there  is  no  response 
on  the  other.  These  are  instances  of  moral  celibacy — in- 
voluntary, however. 

But  celibacy  may  also  be  voluntary,  and  yet  a  matter  of  duty 
(Matt.  xix.  11,  12,  xxii.  30;  Luke  xx.  34-36;  1  Cor.  vii."; 
Eev.  xiv.  4).  For  example,  a  man  may  find  himself  required 
by  his  special  vocation  to  forego  family  life ;  for  man  has  a 
vocation,  whereas  the  sphere  of  a  woman's  vocation  is  the 
family  itself.  So  it  was  with  the  Apostles  Paul  and  Barnabas, 
while  it  is  evident  from  Matt.  xix.  that  Christ  did  not  dis- 
approve of  such  celibacy.  Paul,  too  (1  Cor.  vii.),  though  he  is 
far  from  making  a  merit  of  it,  is  conscious  that  he  is  acting 
morally  in  remaining  unmarried,  as  by  this  means  he  secures 
free  play  for  his  missionary  activity.  Similarly,  we  can 
imagine  a  daughter,  who  has  sick  parents  to  wait  upon,  deny- 
ing herself  for  their  sake  a  home  of  her  own.  It  is  even 
conceivable  that  a  person  may  by  nature  have  no  sexual 
inclinations  at  all,  and  may  even  have  a  repugnance  to  any- 
thing of  the  sort.  As  long  as  this  continues,  marriage  is  of 
course  forbidden,  from  the  want  of  the  requisite  inclination. 
In  fine,  it  cannot  be  said  that  marriage  is  cibsolutely  inclispcnscible 
to  every  one  as  a  means  of  moral  education ;  but  only  that 
family  and  domestic  life  must  be  the  basis  of  such  an  educa- 
tion. And  this  is  possible  to  even  an  unmarried  person  by 
sharing  in  some  circle  of  family  life.  Paul  gives  unmarried 
life  the  preference ;  not  universally,  however,  that  is,  not  in 
every  respect,  but  partly  on  account  of  the  circumstances  of  the 
time  and  the  dangers  connected  with  them,  which  were  greater 
for  families  than  individuals ;  partly  because  those  who  lead 
a  single  life  could  be  more  constant  in  prayer.  He  who 
remains  unmarried  from  motives  of  duty  is  also  more  inde- 
pendent of  the  flesh,  his  sensual  life  is  more  undisturbed ;  but 
his  position  is  not  on  that  account  in  every  respect  a  better 
one,  for  from  another  point  of  view  we  may  say,  that  a  mar- 
ried man  is  able  to  do  more  in  the  way  of  moral  achievement. 
Even  Paul  does  not  see  any  merit  in  celibacy,  does  not  regard 
it  as  a  special  and  higher  condition  of  life.  At  all  events,  it 
is  certain  that  it  is  every  one's  duty,  nnless  he  is  prevented 


MOI^AL  CONTRACTION  OF  MARUIAGE.  537 

on  moral  grounds   from  marrying,  to  seek  to  reap  the  benefits 
of  this  high  and  social  blessing,  this  school  of  virtue. 

(b)  Moral  Contraction  of  Marriage.  Positively,  marriage 
should  be  entered  upon  only  after  "judicious  deliberation,  and 
on  the  ground  of  virtuous  and  proved  mutual  affection  "  (Eothe, 
iii.  640  K).  Since  the  way  in  which  a  marriage  is  contracted 
has  usually  a  decisive  influence  upon  its  whole  character,  the 
most  careful  consideration  is  necessary  in  forming  an  engage- 
ment. Hence  precipitate  engagements  should  be  avoided ; 
an  age  should  first  be  reached  at  which  a  sufficient  degree  of 
discretion  and  experience  has  been  gained.  And  in  taking 
such  a  matter  into  consideration,  the  following  points  should 
especially  be  attended  to  :  first,  none  of  the  physical  conditions 
should  be  wanting  that  are  necessary  to  the  establishment  of 
a  household ;  then  there  should  be  no  incongruity  in  respect 
of  age,  position,  or  religion  ;  further,  there  should  be  an  earnest 
affection  capable  of  lasting,  and  its  necessary  conditions,  an 
affection  not  in  ahstracto,  but  one  to  the  person  in  question ; 
and  finally,  the  two  parties  should  harmonize  in  their  tenden- 
cies and  fundamental  tone  of  character.  This  last  point  does 
not  by  any  means  imply  that  tliey  should  be  exactly  similar; 
for  dissimilarities  go  very  well  together  when  they  supplement 
each  other.  For  any  one  to  form  an  engagement  without  a 
pure  and  tried  affection  is  a  lie  against  the  objective  relation 
itself  and  against  another.  All  passionate  and  extravagant 
courses  also  will  be  found  reprehensible,  when  tested  by 
virtuous  reflection.  For  passion  fades  (§  18).  But  the  most 
important  thing  of  all  is  to  bring  our  resolve  to  God  and 
try  it  before  Him.  He  who  marries  and  does  not  form  tlie 
alliance  as  in  the  presence  of  God,  nay,  who  even  refuses  to 
regard  it  as  a  religious  covenant  at  all,  exposes  himself  to  all 
the  dangers  of  self-deception  and  failure.  The  part  which 
piety  should  play  in  the  contraction  of  marriage  must  be  to 
lead  to  such  a  choice  as  presupposes,  if  not  that  the  other  is 
already  a  Christian,  that  he  or  she  has  at  least  the  will  and 
inclination  to  become  more  and  more  such.^  There  is  no  sure 
basis  for  mutual  confidence,  unless  the  Christian  fear  of  God 
be  present.  This  alone  is  the  foundation  of  wedded  happi- 
ness. To  marry  any  one  in  order  to  convert  him  is  innnoral, 
1  Harless,  p.  436. 


538  §  72.    MAERIAGE. 

for  this  is  a  matter  that  is  not  in  man's  hand.  Also,  since 
family  worship  is  one  of  the  principal  parts  of  domestic  life, 
an  alliance  should  be  sought  after  in  which  such  worship  will 
be  possible,  and  mixed  marriages  of  such  a  sort  as  to  render 
it  impossible  ought  to  be  avoided. 

Further,  since  the  testing  process  mentioned  above  is  a 
serious  matter,  and  since  youth  does  not  possess  the  expe- 
rience of  riper  years,  but  is  swayed  by  passionate  inclinations, 
it  must  be  laid  down  as  a  general  rule  for  the  moral  contrac- 
tion of  marriage,  that  the  choice  made  by  children  needs  to 
be  supplemented  by  the  judgment  of  parents  or  guardians. 
Although  children  must  not  be  forced  into  a  marriage,  and 
are  not  bound,  nay,  are  not  even  justified  in  yielding  obedience 
against  their  inclinations,  it  is  no  less  certain  that  it  is  the 
duty  of  parents  to  refuse  their  consent  to  a  union,  which  they 
feel  convinced  is  pernicious.  It  ill  becomes  children  also,  even 
when  it  is  legally  within  their  power,  to  institute  judicial 
proceedings  and  make  good  their  choice  in  opposition  to  their 
parents.  By  so  doing  they  disturb  that  moral  relation  which 
is  the  older  of  the  two,  and  form  a  new  moral  relation  at  the 
expense  of  one  already  in  existence.  Only  in  the  rarest  and 
most  exceptional  cases  can  it  be  permissible  to  enter  into 
marriage  without  the  consent  and  blessing  of  parents.  Even 
an  engagement  ought  not  to  be  formed  without  at  least  the 
knowledge  of  parents.  To  do  so  would  be  unchildlike,  and 
would  indicate  a  mistrust  that  is  sure  to  do  mischief,  while  it 
would  show  but  little  confidence  in  the  inward  rightness  of 
the  step  that  is  taken. 

In  addition  to  receiving  the  consent  of  parents,  those  who 
enter  into  marriage  must  be  willing,  that  the  new  alliance 
should  be  united  to  the  great  moral  communities  which  sur- 
round us,  and  should  obtain  their  recognition.  The  subjective 
side,  the  free  choice,  requires  (as  we  saw  when  treating  of 
Vocation,  §  68)  to  be  recognised  by  the  other  moral  com- 
munities, with  whicli  the  new  marriage  is  to  be  organically 
connected  on  its  social  side.  And  this  takes  place,  not  only 
through  the  participation  of  parents,  but  also  through  the  civil 
recognition  of  the  State  and  the  consecration  of  the  Church. 
It  is  true  that  neither  Church  nor  State  initiates  the  marriage. 
This  is  done   by  the  wills  of  the   two  persons  who   engage 


MONOGAMY.  539 

themselves  to  each  other ;  hut  the  marriage  is  not  made 
manifest  as  something  that  is  morally  right,  nor  does  it  obtain 
the  social  character  which  is  essential  to  it,  nntil  it  has 
received  that  place  in  the  social  organism  which  is  given  it 
by  the  recognition  of  the  State  and  the  Church.  Accordingly 
it  is  morally  reprehensible  to  anticipate  married  life  in  a 
libertine  manner  before  this  ratification  has  taken  place  [cf. 
p.  546]. 

Note  1. — Those  iclio  are  too  closely  related  ty  hlood  should  net 
marry.  A  family  becomes  enfeebled,  if  new  life  is  not  infused 
into  it  from  others.  It  is  beneficial  to  marriage,  giving  it  strength 
and  character,  when  the  contrast  of  individuality  between  hus- 
band and  wife  is  well  marked.  But  in  the  same  family  this 
contrast,  which  is  so  conducive  to  the  vigour  and  richness  of 
married  life,  is  less  strong.  This  at  least  is  the  case  at  present ; 
in  the  beginning  of  the  human  race  it  may  have  been  different, 
for  then  marriage  took  place  even  between  brother  and  sister. 

Note  2. — A  marriage  should  not  be  formed  witli  an  iLnhdiever, 
especially  when  he  belongs  to  a  non-Christian  religion.  For  a 
marriage  which  excludes  at  the  outset  all  fello^^■ship  in  the 
innermost  sanctuary  of  the  soul,  cannot  be  a  right  one.  Speak- 
ing generally,  too,  marriages  between  Protestants  and  Eoman 
Catholics  are  unadvisable.  But  Christian  ethics  cannot  ab- 
solutely forbid  them.  They  may  turn  out  well,  if  they  are 
accompanied  with  a  special  degree  of  true  Christian  piety.  And 
then,  too,  they  may  serve  the  purpose  of  bringing  Catholic  and 
Evangelical  Christianity  to  view  and  respect,  and,  as  far  as  such 
association  reaches,  to  recognise  each  other.  Tlie  union  of 
Christian  Churches  must  ahvays  be  an  object  of  hope,  and  mixed 
marriages  between  Christians,  when  they  are  prosperous,  may 
be  a  type  of  this  union, — nay,  they  may  be  an  important  means 
of  realizing  it,  for  before  the  Churches  are  united  they  must  first 
know  and  respect  each  other. 

5.  Monogamy  and  tlic  Indissohibleness  of  Marriage.  Mono- 
gamy follows  directly  from  the  very  nature  of  marriage.  For 
marriage  demands  the  complete  and  exclusive  surrender  of 
person  to  person.  The  opposite  principle  would  be,  that  no 
moral  ends  are  involved  in  marriage — a  principle  that  would 
degrade  love  to  a  lower  level.  On  the  corporeal  side  marriage 
has  something  exclusive  about  it,  an  exclusiveness,  however,  that 
serves  as  a  condition  and  background,  as  it  were,  for  brin^iniT; 
out  love  with  all  the  more  intensity.      In  polygamy,  on  the 


540  §  72.    MAE RI AGE, 

other  hand  (and  in  polyandry  mutatis  mutandis),  the  husLand 
has  a  position  of  false  predominance,  and  cannot  give  himself 
np  completely  to  one  of  his  wives.  Polygamy  confirms  him 
in  sensual  egoism  ;  he  soon  becomes  a  lord  instead  of  a  spouse, 
while  marriage  becomes  a  species  of  slavery,  degenerating  into 
a  relation  of  master  and  menials,  which  is  degrading  on  both 
sides.  Still  polygamy  in  the  Old  Testament,  or  wherever  it 
is  sanctioned  by  law  and  custom,  is  not  morally  identical  with 
fornication  and  adultery.  There  is  ydfio<i  even  in  polygamy, 
and  adultery  is  possible  here  as  well  as  in  monogamy.  Hence 
in  the  African  mission  field,  for  instance,  it  is  not  to  be 
demanded  of  a  prince  who  is  living  in  polygamy,  that  he  should 
repudiate  all  his  wives  except  one. 

From  the  essential  character  of  marriage  it  likewise  follows 
that  it  is  indissclaUe.  It  would  be  immoral  to  contract  it 
under  the  reservation  of  possible  separation.  Morally,  it 
must  be  entered  upon  as  for  ever.  Such  a  reservation  would 
mean  a  withholding  of  love  and  loyalty.  If  marriage,  indeed, 
were  only  a  relation  of  contract,  it  might  be  annulled  by 
mutual  agreement.  But  then  its  right,  its  sacredness  as 
an  objective  institution,  would  be  surrendered  to  subjective 
caprice ;  and  this  would  be  sinful,  because  marriage,  and  even 
civil  marriage,  is  in  itself  indissoluble. 

Divorce  is  the  contradiction  of  the  indissolubility  of 
marriage.  Christ  forbids  the  divorce  which  was  permitted, 
though  by  no  means  approved  of,  in  the  Old  Testament  (Deut. 
xxiv.  1  f.  ;  Matt.  v.  31,  32  ;  xix.  3-9  ;  Mark  x.  4  f.).  He 
opposes  the  frivolity  of  practising  divorce  at  pleasure  ;  to 
come  more  closely  to  the  point.  He  forbids  a  separation  on 
the  part  of  either  the  man  or  the  woman  (Mark  x.  12), 
except  it  be  for  iropveia ;  this  exception  referring  not  to  sins 
committed  before  marriage,  nor  merely  to  adultery  in  the 
narrower  sense  of  the  word,  but  to  any  kind  of  unchastity  in 
married  life,  as  for  instance  where  the  woman  allows  herself 
to  be  treated  unchastely.  Whosoever,  He  says,  shall  put 
away  his  wife  {oTrokvar])  ;  and  this  evidently  means  an 
arbitrary  putting  away,  a  repudiation.  The  sacredness  of 
the  objective  relation  ought  to  keep  both  parties  together,  and 
tliis  relation  continues  to  have  claims  upon  a  man,  even  when 
he  has  arbitrarily  withdrawn  from  it.      Christ  expresses  this 


ITS  INDISSOLUBLENESS.  541 

by  saying,  that  he  causes  her  who  is  put  away  to  commit 
adultery.  That  is  to  say,  he  brings  himself  into  a  position 
that  renders  it  impossible  to  restore  the  marriage  that  has 
been  broken,  while  the  ease  with  which  the  separation  is 
effected  makes  it  easy  for  the  woman  to  enter  into  an  adul- 
terous connection  with  another.  Further,  it  is  said  that  he 
that  marrieth  her  that  is  put  away  (that  is,  arbitrarily  and 
invalidly  put  away)  committeth  adultery,  for  he  makes  the 
restoration  of  the  marriage  and  the  duty  of  reconciliation 
impossible.  And,  in  the  third  place,  Christ  adds  as  a  m.atter 
of  course,  that  when  a  man,  who  has  put  away,  i.e.  has  sin- 
fully repudiated,  his  wife,  marries  another  woman,  he  thereby 
violates  a  still  existing  marriage.  In  this  connection  Christ 
always  speaks  of  marrying  again,  because  in  the  case  of  an 
unjust  divorce  it  is  a  second  marriage  that  gives  finality  to 
tlie  separation — that  is,  where  monogamy  prevails.  In  the 
second  marriage  the  sin  of  the  separation  has  reached  its 
climax,  for  any  renewal  of  the  former  relationship  has  now 
become  impossible,  unless  polygamy  were  permissible.  Thus 
we  see,  that  any  arbitrary  exercise  of  authority,  in  the  way  of 
breaking  an  existing  marriage  relationship,  is  censured  by 
Christ  in  the  strongest  terms,  and  represented  by  Him  as 
equivalent  to  the  sin  of  causing  adultery.  Still,  it  is  evident 
that  the  duties  of  that  party  who  is  only  passively  im^plicated 
in  the  separation,  are  not  discussed.  The  words,  "  he  that 
marrieth  her  when  she  is  put  away  committeth  adultery/* 
might  seem  to  signify  that  a  woman  even  when  divorced 
without  any  fault  of  her  own  must  not  marry  again.  But 
Christ  is  here  speaking  of  arbitrary  divorce  by  means  of  a 
bill  of  divorcement.  In  this  case  the  marriage  still  remains 
valid  objectively,  and  is  broken  by  a  second  marriage.  The 
above  saying  of  our  Lord,  therefore,  is  a  warning  against 
divorce  on  frivolous  pretexts,  reminding  His  hearers  that  an 
arbitrary  separation  leads  to  adultery,  to  the  violation  of  a 
marriage  that  ought  to  be  maintained  notwithstanding  the 
l)ill  of  divorcement.  Christ  does  not  take  any  special  notice 
of  the  second  marriage  of  the  innocent  party,  whicli  is  certainly 
a  very  likely  result,  because  He  is  solely  engaged  in  com- 
bating the  arbitrariness  that  prevailed  with  regard  to  divorce. 
St.  Paul;  however,  speaks  of  this  case  in  1  Cor.  vii.  12-16. 


542  §  72.    MARRIAGE. 

The  believing  wife  must  not  separate  from  the  unbeliev- 
ing husband,  and  conversely.  For  it  was  not  Christianity 
that  made  them  man  and  wife,  and  God  can  make  the 
continuance  of  their  marriage  the  means  of  winning  the 
husband  to  the  Christian  faith.  Difference  of  religion 
therefore  affords  no  ground  for  dissolving  a  marriage  that 
has  already  taken  place,  though  it  may  be  a  reason  to 
prevent  a  Christian  from  forming  one.  But  should  the  un- 
hclieving  hitshand  separate  himself  from  his  wife,  then  she  has 
only  a  passive  share  in  the  seijaration.  Here  the  apostle 
does  not  bid  her  to  do  penance  for  the  guilt  of  her  unbeliev- 
ing husband,  who  has  separated  from  her,  nor  to  remain 
exposed  to  trials  of  her  faith  or  to  manifold  sufferings  on 
account  of  her  Christian  profession,  but  says,  that  if  her  un- 
believing husband  will  not  stay  with  her,  she  is  no  longer 
bound  to  him  {ov  BeSovXcoTat),  ver.  15 — a  phrase  which  means, 
according  to  Eom.  vii.  2  f.,  that  her  husband  no  longer  exists 
for  her,  he  is  as  good  as  dead,  and  she  can  proceed  to  form 
a  new  marriage.  According  to  the  apostle,  therefore,  the 
vineidum  may  be  broken  by  something  else  than  death ; 
marriage  has  no  character  indelelilis.  It  may  be  asked, 
why  does  the  apostle  tell  the  woman  that  she  is  free  from 
her  husband,  when  it  may  be  that  the  latter,  although  not  as 
yet  a  believer,  will  become  one  by  and  by ;  why  does  he  not 
expressly  require  her  to  remain  unmarried  in  expectation  of 
this  happy  result  ?  To  this  we  must  reply  that  the  hora 
conversionis  depends  upon  God's  sovereign  power,  and  there- 
fore that  while  nothing  must  be  done  to  hinder  its  coming, 
we  must  not,  in  shaping  our  individual  life,  reckon  upon 
factors  that  God  keeps  in  reserve  and  has  not  yet  permitted 
to  appear.  Accordingly,  cases  may  arise  where  a  woman,  who 
has  been  abandoned  by  her  husband,  may,  from  the  nature  of 
the  circumstances,  enter  upon  a  second  marriage  without  com- 
mitting sin.  Of  course  the  circumstances  of  the  case,  and 
the  individual  relations  between  her  husband  and  herself, 
may  be  such  as  to  leave  room  for  hope  on  his  behalf,  and 
then  it  will  be  both  a  right  and  a  Christian  thing  for  her  to 
wait  in  involuntary  scparatio  a  thoro  et  mensa.  From  causes, 
however,  connected  with  the  man  or  the  woman,  the  circum- 
stances may  point  in  an  opposite  direction,  and  for  this  reason 


ITS  INDISSOLUBLENESS.  543 

tlie  apostle  is  content  with  the  indefinite  ov  SeSovXcorai,  and 
neither  advises  nor  forbids  a  second  marriage.  Further, 
there  are  many  hard  cases  of  marriage  that  occur,  when  a 
scparatio  a  tlioro  d  mcnsa  seems  at  the  first  glance  to  afford  a 
welcome  solution  of  the  difficulty.  And  the  reason  that  the 
apostle  did  not  enjoin  it  as  a  remedy,  may  have  been  that 
experience  teaches  that  a  sc/paratio  which  is  not  final  places 
one  in  danger  of  adultery,  while  if  it  is  final  it  differs  in  no 
respect  from  divorce,  since  marriage  is  only  valid  during  the 
present  life.  Hence  in  the  Eeformation  age  1  Cor.  vii.  was 
appealed  to  as  showing  that  desertion  is  equivalent  to  com- 
pulsory divorce,  as  far  as  the  innocent  party  is  concerned,  and 
that  a  second  marriage  of  the  latter  is  therefore  justifiable. 
Against  this  view  it  has  been  urged,  that  Paul  in  the  above 
passage  specifies  the  particular  case  of  malicious  desertion 
(desertio  malitiosa)  on  the  ground  of  difference  of  religion,  and 
therefore  that  his  words  afford  no  justification  of  a  second 
marriage  in  the  case  of  malicious  desertion  arising  from  other 
causes.  But  if  the  apostle  had  based  the  right  to  marry 
again,  and  consequently  the  right  to  break  the  marriage  bond, 
upon  the  religious  difference  and  not  upon  the  fact  of  desertion, 
he  would  have  been  compelled  to  allow  the  believing  spouse 
to  effect  a  separation  and  marry  again,  even  though  the  un- 
believing one  were  willing  that  the  marriage  should  continue. 
Eut  this  he  absolutely  forbids.  Consequently  it  is  the 
separation,  the  dissolution  of  marriage  through  desertion, 
upon  which  the  apostle  rests  his  declaration  that  the 
deserted  spouse  is  free,  and  we  must  agree  with  the 
Eeformers  in  placing  clcscrtio  malitiosa  alongside  of  iropveia 
as  a  valid  ground  of  divorce.^  But,  of  course,  desertio  malitiosa 
as  such  must  be  clearly  proved,  and  proved  to  be  obdurate. 
For  otherwise,  and  if  there  were  any  want  of  foresight  and 
strictness  in  this  respect,  any  wish  on  the  part  of  a  married 
couple  to  be  separated  from  each  other  could  be  carried  out 
without  trouble.  For  this  desire  for  separation  could  by  a 
preconcerted  arrangement  take  the  garb  of  desertio  malitiosa ; 
the  deserted  spouse  would  no  longer  have  merely  a  passive 

^  We  are  less  able  to  agree  witli  them,  however,  when  they  treat  the  refusal 
of  conjugal  rights  as  desertio  malitiosa  ;  for  even  in  such  a  case  the  greater 
part  of  the  fellowship  of  married  life  may  still  subsist. 


544  §  72.    MARKIAGE. 

share  in  the  transaction,  and  the  most  frivolous  of  all  kinds 
of  divorce,  viz.  divorce  on  the  ground  of  mutual  dislike,  might 
clothe  itself  in  this  form. 

In  addition  to  adultery  and  malicious  desertion,  are  there  still 
other  grounds  of  divorce  recognised  in  the  New  Testament  ? 
It  has  been  held  that  such  grounds  might  be  inferred  from 
Matt.  V.  by  taking  Tra/je/cro?  Xojov  iropveia'i  to  mean — except 
in  cases  which  fall  within  the  category  of  iropvela.  Accordingly, 
by  adopting  this  meaning  the  so-called  ^jft?"  ratio  has  been  set 
up,  and  it  has  been  said,  that  wherever  there  is  a  ground  of 
divorce  the  same  as,  or  similar  to  adultery,  divorce  may  take 
place.  But  the  passage  Matt.  xix.  9  has  merely  /i^  eVt 
iropvela,  and  this  does  not  admit  of  other  cases  being  included. 
Mark  and  Luke  also  do  not  mention  iropvela.  A  more  im- 
portant question  is,  what  is  the  meaning  of  irapeKTO';  Xoyou 
TTopveiai;  ?  Every  divorce,  Christ  says,  is  sin  ;  but  there  are 
cases  where  it  is  not  sin  to  effect  a  divorce — the  innocent  party 
being,  of  course,  here  referred  to.  It  is  certain  that  adultery  is 
also  meant.  But  Trapveca  is  a  wider  idea.  There  are  sins  against 
marriage  which  are  not  adultery  in  the  narrower  sense  of  the 
word,  and  yet  destroy  marriage  irretrievably,  while  the  degree 
of  guilt  attaching  to  adulteiy  may  vary  very  coaisiderably. 
Now  marriage  may  be  destroyed  in  two  main  ways,  corre- 
sponding to  the  idea  of  marriage,  which  is  compounded  of  both 
the  physical  and  the  spiritual  (par.  3).  («)  The  physical 
side,  which  is  essential  to  the  idea,  may  be  withheld,  either 
through  desertio  malitiosa,  of  which  the  apostle  speaks,  or 
through  adultery  with  a  third  person,  which  comes  under  the 
head  of  iropveia  (Matt.  v.).  (l>)  The  spiritual  side  may  be 
entirely  withdrawn  ;  love,  for  instance,  may  be  lost,  husband 
and  wife  lay  snares  for  each  other's  life,  there  may  be  attempts 
at  murder,  the  one  may  endeavour  to  ruin  the  other  in  body, 
in  soul,  or  in  reputation  ;  the  husband  may  try  to  force  his 
wife  to  prostitution,  or  may  persist  in  living  a  dissolute  life, 
utterly  regardless  of  the  duty  of  supporting  wife  and  children, 
and  may  thus  in  the  language  of  the  apostle  be  worse  than  a 
lieathen.  Here  love,  the  first  requisite  in  marriage,  no  longer 
exists,  but  is  changed  into  hatred  and  malignity.  In  such  a 
case,  the  only  part  of  marriage  tliat  remains  is  the  physical 
side;   but  a   cohahitatio   that   is  merely   physical,   and   from 


ITS  INDISSOLUBLENESS.  545 

which  all  love  and  affection  have  disappeared,  is  simply 
'TTopvela  (§  18).  If  in  these  circumstances  the  marriage 
relation  were  still  kept  up,  the  injured  spouse  would  be 
degraded  by  being  used  merely  as  a  means  of  satisfying 
sexual  desire,  a  desire  into  which  no  love  would  enter,  and 
which  would  therefore  not  be  human,  but  solely  animal. 
Accordingly  Christ  says,  fi-q  eirl  iropveia  (Matt.  xix.  9)  ; 
marriage  must  not  exist  for  the  sake  of  iropveia.  And 
therefore,  where  the  spiritual  elements  of  love  and  affection 
are  wanting,  neither  State  nor  Church  can  compel  husband  and 
wife  to  live  together,  because  marriage  must  not  be  turned 
into  iropveia.  Thus  we  adhere  to  the  words  of  Christ  and 
His  apostles  when  we  take  up  the  following  position.  On 
the  one  hand,  we  do  not  regard  marriage  as  being  something 
of  the  nature  of  dogma,  purely  divine,  and  indestructible — in 
other  words,  as  a  sacrament ;  we  regard  it,  on  the  contrary,  as 
also  an  dliical  product,  and  therefore  as  both  exposed  to  the 
danger  of  being  destroyed  and  as  delivered  up  to  loyal  and 
moral  keeping.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  we  give  no  counten- 
ance to  divorce,  or  to  second  marriage  on  the  part  of  those 
who  have  been  divorced,  unless  it  can  be  proved  that  the 
marriage  has  been  broken  in  one  of  the  two  chief  ways  above 
mentioned.  For  to  do  so  would  be  to  favour  the  breaking  of 
an  obligation  still  in  force  for  both  husband  and  wife,  the 
obligation,  namely,  of  continuing  their  married  life.^  When 
both  parties  are  Christians,  no  such  thing  as  divorce  can 
take  place.  But  when  this  is  not  the  case,  marriage  may  be 
destroyed  by  sin,  and  it  may  be  necessary  (as  with  the  Jews 
under  the  Old  Testament  dispensation)  to  make  allowance  for 
hardness  of  heart,  in  order  that  the  evil  may  not  be  made 
worse.^ 


^  That  disease,  even  mental  disease,  does  not  sever  the  marriage  tie,  results 
from  the  facts,  that  it  is,  on  the  contrary,  a  summons  to  increased  conjugal 
fidelity  and  support,  and  that  it  can  never  be  absolutely  certain  that  recovery 
is  impossible. 

-  Remarriage  following  divorce  is  in  general  unadvisable.  For  it  becomes 
even  the  innocent  party  to  acknowledge  that  he  (or  she)  is  not  without  fault, 
were  it  only  in  having  entered  upon  a  marriage  that  had  afterwards  to  be  dis- 
solved. He  should  therefore  be  inclined  to  misti'ust  himself,  and  not  only  to 
fear  committing  fresh  blunders,  but  also  to  doubt  his  own  fitness  and  vocation 
for  married  life. 

2   M 


546  §  72.    MABEIAGE. 

INote. — Relation  of  State  and  Church  to  Marriage}  Neither 
the  State  nor  the  Church  makes  or  contracts  a  marriage.  But 
it  is  the  duty  of  Christians  to  seek  the  recognition  of  both,  and 
also  to  become  members  as  married  people  of  the  moral  com- 
munities. At  an  earlier  period  this  was  done  by  a  single  act, 
the  nuptial  rite  of  the  Church,  without  which  marriage  was 
not  recognised  as  such  by  the  State ;  at  present  two  acts  are 
required,  the  so-called  civil  act  and  the  wedding.  This  corre- 
sponds with  the  two  sides  of  marriage,  for  marriage  is  essentially 
a  legally  moral  association,  and  is  to  become  a  religiously  moral 
association.  The  legal  side  comes  first  in  conformity  with  the 
whole  structure  of  Ethics,  according  to  which  an  advance  is  to 
be  made  from  eudajmonism,  through  the  stage  of  law  on  to  the 
stage  of  Christianity.  Natural  sexual  intercourse  is  raised  and 
ennobled  through  the  idea  of  law.  Law  is  the  negative  con- 
dition of  the  ethical,  and  therefore  precedes  the  positively 
ethical.  It  belongs  to  the  State,  as  the  public  administrator  of 
law,  to  fix  the  conditions  requisite  to  its  recognition  of  marriage, 
and  to  bring  individual  marriages  under  the  sanction  and  pro- 
tection of  public  law.  Since  this  is  the  case,  the  power  which 
the  Church  once  possessed  of  giving  legal  validity  to  marriage 
could  only  have  arisen,  from  its  acting  in  the  name  or  by 
mandate  of  the  State.  Hence  there  can  be  no  doubt  about 
these  two  propositions:  (1)  The  State, which  had  entrusted  the 
Church  with  the  right  of  acting  in  its  name,  could  without 
injustice  withdraw  this  right  in  order  to  exercise  it  itself;  and 
(2)  when  it  does  exercise  this  right,  its  action  must  precede 
that  of  the  Church,  because  objective  right  or  law  is  the  basis 
of  all  that  follows  [cf.  §  33a.  2]. 

The  earlier  arrangement,  according  to  whicli  the  Church's 
performance  of  the  nuptial  ceremony  included  the  civil  act  as 
well,  while  it  afforded  certain  advantages  also  involved  various 
drawbacks,  especially  in  cases  of  remarriage  on  the  part  of 
those  who  had  been  divorced.  For  no  one  could  be  married 
without  the  rites  of  the  Church,  and  yet  the  Church  could 
not  recognise  many  of  the  grounds  upon  which  divorce  was' 
sanctioned  by  the  State  (by  Prussian  statute-law  in  particular). 
Now,  when  a  divorce  of  this  kind  had  been  permitted  by  the 
State,  the  Church  was  bound,  not  indeed  to  look  upon  the 
nuptial  tie  as  still  existing,  but  to  regard  the  separated  parties 
as  still  under  the  moral  obligation  of  endeavouring  to  restore 
their  previous  connection.  A  second  marriage,  however, 
rendered  such  a  restoration  absolutely  impossible ;  the  Church, 

^  [In  this  note  I  have  followed  the  lectures  of  1879,  since  these  presuppose 
recent  legislation ;  but  have  added  certain  additions  from  the  lectures  of 
previous  years  iu  the  form  of  footnotes.] 


CIVIL  MAKEIAGE.  547 

therefore,  could  not  take  part  in  it  by  performing  the  nuptial 
rite,  inasmuch  as  the  latter  would  have  meant  the  formation  of  a 
nciv  marriage.  The  State,  again,  on  its  side  could  not  but  permit 
a  second  marriage  to  those  whom  it  declared  legally  divorced, 
and  such  a  permission  could  not  take  effect  as  long  as  the  rites 
of  the  Church  were  necessary  to  give  legal  validity  to  marriage. 
Thus,  without  taking  the  Old  Catholics  into  account,  whose 
Church  refuses  to  sanction  any  such  remarriage,  the  State  had 
good  grounds,  even  for  the  sake  of  the  Evangelical  Church,  to 
assume  the  control  of  marriage  on  its  legal  side.^ — There  are 
two  ways  in  which  these  collisions  might  have  been  avoided 
without  splitting  up  the  one  act  into  two.  On  the  one  hand, 
the  State  law  of  divorce  might  have  been  so  improved  that  the 
Church,  as  it  had  so  long  done,  could  have  continued  to  go 
hand  in  hand  with  the  State,  and  all  remarriages  of  divorced 
parties  might  have  been  recognised  by  Church  and  State  alike.^ 
Or  on  the  other,  the  Church  might  have  excluded  from  her 
communion  all  those  who  had  procured  divorce  in  a  sinful  way, 
that  the  Church  could  not  recognise.  But  the  Church  lacked 
an  order  of  discipline ;  and  in  addition  to  this,  it  could  not 
have  excommunicated  every  one  who   had   been  wrongfully 

•  In  addition  to  this,  there  were  citizens,  in  the  full  enjoyment  of  their 
natural  rights,  who  had  merely  an  external  connection  with  the  Evangelical 
Church,  which  held  the  ratification  of  marriage  in  its  hands.  The  points  of 
view  of  State  and  Church  with  regard  to  marriage  fall  asrtnder  as  soon  as  the 
Church  on  the  one  side  seeks  to  act  as  a  Chiu'ch,  that  is,  to  apply  Christian 
principles  to  marriage,  while  having  on  the  other  within  her  communion 
people  who  ought  not  to  belong  to  her,  but  to  the  State  alone.  For  these  ought 
to  be  treated,  so  far  as  marriage  is  concerned,  in  accordance  with  the  universal 
principle  of  right ;  that  is  to  say,  they  are  justified  in  demanding  that  unbelief, 
sin,  and  disobedience  to  the  Church  should  not  in  themselves  deprive  them  of 
the  right  to  marry.  For  that  those  M'ho  do  not  live  a  Christian  life  should  be 
robbed  of  the  right  to  marry,  would  be  wholly  opposed  to  the  attitude  of 
Christianity  in  the  matter,  since  she  7-ecognises  the  validity  of  both  pre-Chriatiaii 
and  extra-Christian  marriages. 

^  This  was  what  v.  Bethmann  -  Holhveg  desired.  But  in  vain  ;  the  First 
Chamber  refused  its  assistance,  for  it  introduced  civil  marriage  as  an  optional 
form.  [The  author's  opinion  is  that  the  State  should  have  reformed  its  divorce 
laws.]  "The  norm  by  which  we  must  decide,  whether  a  marriage  still  subsists 
or  not  is  the  same,  whether  we  look  at  the  matter  from  the  point  of  view  of 
private  or  of  public  right.  It  is  true  that  the  words  of  Christ  are  addressed  not 
to  State  and  Church,  but  to  the  conscience  of  the  individual.  But  since  the 
idea  of  marriage  which  they  set  up  is  the  true  moral  one,  there  is  no  necessity 
for  Church  and  State  disagreeing  with  and  contradicting  each  other  in  their 
mode  of  dealing  with  marriage."  [This,  however,  does  not  imply  that  the 
State  cannot  assume  the  legal  control  of  marriage,  more  especially  as  it  must 
take  into  consideration  such  as  are  not  members  of  the  Church  [vid.  supra), 
since  marriage  does  not  depend  upon  Christianity  for  its  existence.] 


548  §  72.    MARFJAGE. 

divorced.  And  as  long  as  these  remained  in  the  Church,  tlie 
collision  we  have  described  would  have  arisen  whenever  they 
wanted  to  marry ;  the  State  would  have  admitted  their  right 
to  marry  again,  the  Church  would  have  denied  it,  and  yet  she 
alone  would  have  had  the  right  to  conclude  a  legal  marriage.^ 

Hence  it  is  clear — (1)  that  the  conduct  of  the  State  was 
neither  illegal  nor  arbitrary ;  and  (2)  that  the  act  of  the  Legis- 
lature was  a  relief  to  the  Church,  as  it  saved  her  from  coming 
into  collision  with  the  State,  and  delivered  her  from  the 
responsibility  of  taking  away  all  possibility  of  marriage  from 
one  who  perhaps  needed  to  be  married,  and  who  in  the  eye  of 
the  State  was  entitled  to  marry. 

When  civil  marriage  is  introduced,  the  Church  has  quite  a 
different  jJosition  witJi  regard  to  the  contraction  of  rnarriage. 
It  is  no  longer  the  Church  that  gives  it  validity.  For  even 
civil  marriage  must  be  recognised  by  the  Church  as  morally 
binding,  and  not  as  a  mere  matter  of  contract.  Since,  then,  she 
has  no  longer  anything  to  do  with  the  contraction  of  marriage, 
and  the  parties  who  come  to  her  for  the  performance  of  nuptial 
rites  are  already  husband  and  wife  in  the  eye  of  the  law,  she 
must  receive  them  as  sucli ;  and  hence,  even  should  either 
of  them  have  been  previously  divorced  on  wrong  and  sinful 
grounds,  she  must  accept  the  divorce  as  an  accomplished  fact, 
and  regard  the  former  marriage  as  irretrievably  broken  by  the 
new  marriage,^  the  civil  act.  In  these  circumstances,  it  becomes 
the  duty  and  the  task  of  the  Church  to  bring  her  moral  influence 
to  bear  iipon  the  relation  that  has  been  formed  by  the  civil  act, 
which,  though  sinful  in  its  origin,  is  still  binding.  For  this 
end  she  must  use  all  the  means  at  her  command,  must  exhort, 
reprove,  declare  the  promises  of  God,  and  demand  of  both 
parties  a  vow  of  mutual  fidelity.  On  the  other  hand,  she  must 
do  nothing  in  the  way  of  endeavouring  to  dissolve  the  connec- 
tion. The  relation  itself  must  not  be  characterized  as  sinful, — 
for  in  that  case  its  dissolution  would  be  a  duty, — but  only  as 

^  This  last  point  must  evidently  be  understood  in  the  following  way. 
Marriage  might  have  continued  to  be  solemnized  by  means  of  a  single  act, 
at  once  ecclesiastical  and  civil,  if  the  Church  had  excommunicated  all  those 
who  in  her  opinion  had  been  unlawfully  divorced.  For  in  that  case  the  Church 
could  .still,  as  formerly,  have  effected  for  the  State  as  well  a  marriage  between  her 
oum  members.  But  then  civil  marriage  would  still  have  been  necessary  to  meet 
the  case  of  those  who  had  been  excommunicated  by  the  Church  (p.  547,  note  1) ; 
and,  in  addition  to  this,  such  excommunication  as  is  here  supposed  is  (as  has 
been  said  above)  impracticable. 

-  It  is  only  before  the  new  marriage  has  taken  place  that  the  Church  can  urge 
the  duty  of  the  separated  couple  to  become  reconciled  to  each  other.  If  either  of 
them  marries  a  second  time,  the  Church  must  not  desire  to  bring  them  together 
again  :  for  this  would  be  bigamy. 


§  73.    THE  FAMILY,  549 

one  that  has  come  into  existence  tliroiKjli  sin.  And,  indeed, 
unless  this  last  fact  be  acknowledged,  there  is  little  hope  that 
the  new  marriaoe  will  turn  out  better  than  the  old  one.^ 


CHAPTER  SECOND. 

THE  FAMILY. 

§73. 

Marriage  is  the  bosom  of  the  family,  which  is  born  of  it,  and 
the  family  again  is  the  bosom,  in  which  lie  the  civil 
and  the  religious  community,  not  as  yet  separated 
from  it.  Christian  family  life  is  maintained  by  means 
of  the  Christian  fainily  spirit,  which  is  natural  family 
affection  raised  to  a  higher  form  of  energy.  Christian 
affection,  which  is  the  ruling  influence  in  the  Christian 
family,  takes  three  specifically  distinct  forms :  («) 
parental  love ;  (6)  love  of  brothers  and  sisters ;  (c) 
filial  love.  The  stream  of  love,  taking  its  rise  from  the 
parents,  arouses  a  responsive  love  on  the  part  of  the 
child,  and  the  latter  both  turns  to  the  source  from 
which  it  came,  and  extends  to  those  who  are  born 
of  the  same  parents. 

1.  The  family  is  an  image  of  the  kingdom  of  God;  in  it 
are  the  germs  of  every  moment  in  the  latter  (§  71).  But 
more  especially  is  the  relation  of  parents  to  children  an  image 
of  the  relation  of  God  to  men,  of  religious  fellowship.  As 
the  love  of  God  owes  its  overmastering  power  to  its  pure, 
undeserved,  prevenient  character,  so  is  it  also  parental  love 
that  kindles  in  cliildren  the  first  sparks  of  filial  love,  and  thus 
awakens  in  them  the  first  sense  of  human  life.  Especially  is 
it  the  loving  eye  of  the  mother,  which,  resting  upon  the  child, 

1  The  Church  should  find  in  civil  marriage  an  incentive  to  private  pastoral 
work  ;  and  she  will  do  well  not  to  wait  for  the  opportunity  afforded  by  divorce, 
before  she  combats  the  loose  morality  that  prevails  in  this  matter.  It  is  her 
duty  to  purify  and  shape  public  opinion,  to  bring  back  the  pure  idea  of  the 
sanctity  of  marriage  to  the  consciousness  of  the  people,  and  to  quicken  their 
conscience  by  ivord  and  doctrine. 


550  §  73.    THE  FAMILY. 

makes  it  conscious  that  it  is  loved,  aud  wins  its  love  in  return. 
Christian  marriage  not  only  begets,  but  educates  children ; 
it  regards  them  as  personalities  made  in  the  image  of  God,  a 
fact  to  which  the  Church  bears  witness  in  infant  baptism. 
For  baptism  shows  that  children  are  received  into  the  fellow- 
ship of  God  and  Christ,  and  into  the  Church.  The  whole 
education  of  the  child  must  be  directed  by  the  ideal  of  hajjtism, 
since  baptism  is  the  representation  of  the  central  and  supreme 
sphere.  This  education  devolves  upon  the  parents,  as  being 
the  persons  who  are  qualified  by  affection  for  the  task.  But 
it  has  also  a  public  aspect,  and  hence  there  are  public  schools. 
Everything  here  depends  upon  both  parents  working  har- 
moniously together,  the  characteristic  differences  of  the  sexes 
being  brought  into  play.  Mothers  are  apt  to  be  vain  and 
indulgent,  even  in  their  self-sacrificing  love,  and  then  the 
egoism  of  the  little  ones  is  developed.  Fathers  again,  realizing 
vividly  the  goal  of  education,  incline  towards  impatience,  may 
make  too  stringent  demands,  and  become  imperious.  These 
tendencies  must  in  both  cases  be  restrained  by  love.  In 
particular,  it  is  the  seriousness  of  the  father,  as  he  exercises 
the  right  and  discharges  the  duty  of  a  priest  in  family 
worship,  that  arouses  the  conscience  of  the  child  at  an  early 
stage,  and  gives  to  natural  love  a  moral  tone.  Authority  in 
the  family  rests  upon  the  mutual  co-operation  of  both  parents. 
They  are  the  autores  vitoi  of  the  child,  of  its  physical  life  to 
begin  with,  and  then  of  spiritual  life  too,  which  ought  to  be 
implanted  in  tlie  child  through  their  agency.  In  performing 
this  duty,  parents  have  at  first  simply  to  give,  while  children 
are  merely  receptive.  The  reason  of  the  parents  lives  in  the 
children,  and  takes  the  place  of  reason  in  them.  But  educa- 
tion has  for  its  purpose  to  train  up  children  to  l^e  capable 
men  and  women  both  in  body  and  mind,  i.e.  to  be  true 
Christians,  worthy  members  of  the  State  and  of  the  Church. 
In  the  family,  two  generations  are  side  by  side,  and  it  is  meant 
that  the  blessings  enjoyed  by  the  earlier  one  should  be  handed 
down  to  the  later,  in  order  that  the  great  boon  of  Christianity 
itself  may  continually  increase  and  develope,  and  sons  become 
better  than  their  fathers  were.  Children  are  the  issue  of 
their  parents,  and  so  their  natural  heirs.  The  aim  of  educa- 
tion is  to  briniT  the  child   to  man's  estate.      But   for  this  end 


OBEDIENCE.  551 

obedience  is  reqiured.  From  this  often  bitter  root  grows  the 
sweet  fruit  of  liberty.  The  exercise  of  authority  in  a  Christian 
family  does  not  mean,  that  harsh  and  despotic  measures  are 
employed,  producing  alienation  between  parents  and  children ; 
on  the  contrary,  it  is  conscience  that  is  influenced,  and  affection 
that  is  quickened.  Neither  does  the  obedience  required  imply, 
that  in  parents  children  see  only  their  masters  ^  (Heb. 
xii.  7).  The  apostle  demands  that  children  he  not  discouraged 
(Eph.  vi.  4  ;  Col.  iii.  21).  Parental  authority  ought  truly  to  be 
in  God's  stead,  and  to  take  the  place  of  reason  in  the  child, 
and  then  tlie  obedience  of  children  is  not  legal  but  spontaneous, 
being  based  upon  the  consciousness  of  parental  love  (Col.  iii. 
20,  21). 

2.  The  cardinal  virtue  of  the  child  is  obedience  (Eph.  vi. 
1  f. ;  Coh  iii.  20;  1  Tim.  iii.  4;  Tit.  i.  6).  Obedience  must 
not  only  be  rendered,  when  the  child  is  convinced  that  the 
will  of  its  parents  is  substantially  right.  For  if  children  were 
only  to  obey  under  these  conditions,  they  would  then  merely 
obey  themselves.  On  the  contrary,  parents  must  stand  in 
God's  stead  to  the  child,  and  the  formal  obligation  of  obedience 
must  extend  to  matters  which  as  yet  he  does  not  understand, 
and  for  which  the  parents  alone  can  be  responsible.  Filial 
love  is  maintained  by  reverence  and  gratitude  towards  parents, 
in  accordance  with  the  example  of  Christ  (Luke  ii.  51  f.).  It 
is  from  their  parents  that  children  derive  their  first  knowledge 
of  God.  Eeverence  is  evinced  in  the  open  sincerity  with 
which  obedience  is  yielded.  Gratitude  finds  employment  in 
prayer  on  behalf  of  the  parents ;  at  a  later  period  the  parts 
of  parents  and  children  are  reversed ;  it  is  the  parents  that 
are  helpless,  it  is  the  children  that  give  their  help,  but  always 
in  the  same  attitude  of  filial  gratitude  (John  xix.  26  f.).  The 
greatest  difficulty  of  all  arises  at  the  period  of  transition  from 
minority  to  full  maturity.  It  is  difficult  for  parents  to  hit  the 
due  measure  of  independence  to  be  accorded  to  their  children. 
On  the  one  hand,  parents  should  keep  clearly  in  mind,  that 
their  children  must  be  bound  to  them  by  ties  of  confidence 
and  gratitude ;  at  the  same  time  it  is  no  less  incumbent  upon 
the  children  to  remember,  that  even  should  their  emancipatioii 
be  long  in  coming,  they  ought  not  to  assert  their  rights  and 
^  Employment  of  children  in  factories  =  slavery. 


552  §  74.    EXTENSION  OF  THE  HOUSEHOLD. 

claims,  or  the  duties  of  their  parents  towards  them ;  for  mere 
duty  and  justice  form  an  alien  and  a  fatal  point  of  view  for 
the  warm  affection  which  ought  to  characterize  the  whole 
sphere  of  family  and  married  life.  It  is  far  better  that 
children  should  remain  in  subjection  to  their  parents  longer 
than  is  necessary,  than  that  they  should  assert  their  liberty 
in  mistrust  and  thanklessness.  It  must  not  be  left  to  children 
to  decide  for  themselves  when  they  should  become  indepen- 
dent ;  here,  too,  there  must  be  an  objective  testimony  coincid- 
ing with  subjective  opinion.  What  we  have  already  said  in 
§  68  holds  good  in  this  case  as  well,  with  the  omission  of  the 
limitations  that  had  then  to  be  introduced.  And  even  should 
the  most  unfavourable  circumstances  arise,  the  age  of  majority 
as  fixed  by  the  State  assures  the  independence  of  the  child. 

3.  Love  hetivecn  brothers  and  sisters,  again,  is  an  affection  of 
an  altogether  peculiar  kind,  distinct  from  friendship,  in  having 
a  basis  in  nature.  As  nat^io'al,  it  is  a  type  of  Christian  love 
for  one's  neighbour,  while  as  Christian  it  is  a  special  and 
closer  form  of  the  same.  This  love  (and  what  we  say  holds 
good  of  collateral  as  well  as  of  lineal  connections)  is  essentially 
a  relation  of  co-ordination,  even  where  great  differences  exist 
with  respect  to  age.  Younger  brothers  and  sisters  know  this 
very  well.  This  form  of  affection,  too,  is  the  means  by  which 
a  transition  is  made  from  the  life  of  the  family  to  the  spheres 
that  lie  outside  of  it,  especially  as  children  ought  not  to  confine 
themselves  to  the  household  to  which  they  belong,  but  ought 
to  seek  society  of  a  wider  kind.  Family  spirit  can  only  be 
kept  from  becoming  narrow  and  restricted  by  free  intercourse 
with  other  circles. 

CHAPTER  THIED. 

EXTENSION  OF  THE  HOUSEHOLD  BY  MEANS  OF  FRIENDS,  GUESTS, 
AND  SERVANTS. 

§  u. 

While  the  household  is  a  sanctuary  that  maintains  its  position 
of  relative  seclusion,  it  admits  of  extension  in  two  ways. 
On  the  one  hand,  associations  are  formed  with  individuals 


FRIENDS,  GUESTS,  AND  SERVANTS.  5o3 

Lelonging  to  other  liouseliolds,  or  other  spheres  of  life. 
Thus  arise  the  relations  of  host  and  guest,  of  masters 
and  servants,  the  former  being  one  of  essential  equality, 
the  latter  of  inequality.  On  the  other  liand,  the  family 
as  a  whole,  and  through  the  father  as  its  representative, 
enters  into  vital  connection  with  the  public  body  cor- 
porate, both  with  the  so-called  secular  community,  that 
is,  civil  society  and  the  State,  and  with  the  ecclesiastical 
community.  In  the  latter  case,  this  takes  place  with 
reference  both  to  a  particular  congregation,  and  to  the 
larger  ecclesiastical  organism,  whose  basis  is  a  common 
confession. 

1.  We  have  already  spoken  in  §  70  of  family  friendships 
and  hospitality  (Heb.  xiii.  2;  Eom.  xii.  13;  1  Pet.  iv.  9). 
Here,  since  the  family  has  the  most  to  do  in  the  way  of 
giving,  it  would  seem  to  hold  a  position  of  superiority  towards 
its  guests.  But  inasmuch  as  it  must  feel  it  an  honour  to  be 
permitted  to  give,  the  inequality  is  at  once  removed,  and  a 
relation  of  equality  established,  even  apart  from  the  reciprocity 
of  the  relation,  which  extends  also  to  the  privilege  of  giving. 
The  host  must  not  become  a  mere  patron,  nor  the  family 
friend  a  mere  chaperon.  In  exercising  hospitality,  a  family 
takes  pleasure  in  admitting  others  to  witness  its  household 
comfort  and  happiness:  but  it  is  necessary  that  married  and 
family  life  should  have  a  definite  and  substantial  worth  in 
itself,  before  it  can  do  this  properly.  In  the  case  of  many 
families,  however,  hospitality  is  only  a  display  of  their  own 
inward  emptiness — the  home,  which  is  like  a  State  wholly 
occupied  with  other  States,  that  is,  nothing  but  a  ministry 
of  foreign  affairs,  which  cannot  be  carried  on  without  a 
large  amount  of  false  show  and  artifice,  is  merely  a  distrac- 
tion and  delusion.  For  no  one  can  give  anything  to  others, 
unless  he  is  first  of  all  a  personality  concentrated  in  himself. 

2.  Servants.  Servants  are  taken  into  the  households  of 
those  who  are  better  off  as  to  outward  means ;  and  these, 
while  occupying  an  inferior  position,  ought  to  be  made  sharers 
in  the  blessing  of  Christian  family  life,  and  in  the  benefits 
enjoyed  by  their  superiors.      The  more  the  relation  between 


554  §  75.    THE  STATE. 

masters  find  servants  rests  upon  a  onerc  hargain  (altliougli  this 
must  ever  be  the  basis  of  the  relation,  §§  17,  18,  33a),  the 
more  imjjcrfed  it  is ;  while  the  more  it  is  inspired  by  fidelity 
and  attacliment  on  the  part  of  the  servants,  and  by  confidence 
and  kindness  on  the  part  of  the  masters,  the  more  Christian 
does  it  become.  Here,  too,  the  bond  that  should  unite  them 
(as  opposed  to  the  merely  natural  or  legal  relation;  cf.  §§  17, 
23,  33a)  is  the  consciousness,  that  in  the  absolute  sphere,  or 
in  the  presence  of  God,  masters  and  servants  are  equal  (Jas. 
i.  9,  10  ;  Eph.  vi.  5-9;  Col.  iii.  22  f.,  iv.  1  ;  Tit.  ii.  9,  10). 
At  the  present  day,  complaints  with  regard  to  the  servant 
class  are  particularly  rife.  But  in  this  matter  masters  and 
mistresses  have  more  to  answer  for  than  they  will  acknow- 
ledge, nay,  the  chief  share  of  the  blame  falls  to  them.  For 
servants  should  be  incited  to  virtuous  conduct  by  the  spon- 
taneous love  that  is  shown  them,  by  those  who  are  their 
superiors  both  in  rank  and  in  age. 

The  household,  including  servants,  is  a  miniature  of  the 
State  and  the  Church.  The  family,  as  an  organization 
animated  by  love  and  ruled  by  wisdom,  is  at  once  a  State  and 
a  Church,  and  accordingly  has  a  system,  a  discipline,  and  a 
worship  of  its  own. 


SECOND  SECTION. 

THE  MORAL  COMMUNITIES,  WHICH  ARE  THE  PRODUCT  OF 
REELECTION  OR  OF  HUMAN  ART. 

CHAPTER  FIEST. 

THE  STATE. 
§   75. 

Idea  of  the  State  and  its  Relation  to  other  Moral  Organisms. 

The  State  is  not  merely  a  family  on  a  gigantic  scale  ;  neither 
is  it  the  moral  community  pure  and  simple ;  nor,  finally, 
is  it  the  mere  sum  of  the  various  departments  of  human 


THE  STATE.  bo5 

life  which  it  includes.  On  the  contrary,  although  it 
embraces  within  itself  and  in  its  own  way  all  the  other 
ethical  spheres,  just  as  they,  on  the  other  hand,  embrace 
it,  it  is  an  independent  ethical  fabric,  with  an  ethical 
principle  of  its  own.  For  it  is  the  earthly  embodiment 
of  public  justice ;  its  function  in  the  life  of  a  nation  is 
to  be  the  representative  of  the  Divine  authority  of  Eight ; 
and  this  function  it  has  to  discharge  with  the  necessity 
of  a  force  of  nature,  and  therefore  by  means  of  com- 
pulsion and  power.  Like  marriage,  the  State  is  neither 
a  direct  creation  of  God  nor  something  that  is  wholly 
secular ;  but  it  is  a  human  product  resting  on  a  Divine 
basis,  and  thus  has  both  a  Divine  and  a  hum.an  side. 
Since  the  State  is  founded  upon  the  principle  of  right, 
we  can  deduce  from  this  principle  those  essential  claims 
which  must  be  made  of  the  State,  and  by  the  fundamental 
denial  of  which  it  would  cease  to  exist.  But  right  has 
its  formal  and  its  material  side,  and  these  must  be  dis- 
tinguished. It  attains  its  perfect  form  when  it  receives 
the  form  of  law.  And  this  it  does  most  completely  when 
law  is  brought  to  pass  by  a  law  of  the  Legislature  called 
a  constitution.  With  regard  to  their  contents,  right  and 
law  have  a  variable  side,  depending  on  change  of  circum- 
stances and  needs.  Nevertheless  a  continuity  of  right 
is  morally  possible  and  necessary,  and  is  maintained  in 
the  following  way,  without  detriment  to  tlie  variableness 
or  changeableness  above  adverted  to.  The  authorized 
legislative  power — not,  however,  any  revolutionary  force, 
whether  on  the  part  of  rulers  or  subjects — reforms  and 
improves  right  and  law  so  far  as  their  contents  are 
concerned  ;  and  thus,  while  formal  continuity  is  preserved, 
it  becomes  possible  both  for  right  and  the  State  to  have 
a  history.  Since  every  State  presupposes  a  common 
history  of  the  land  and  the  people,  and  since  every 
nation  is  animated  by  its  own  peculiar  national  spirit, 


556  §  75.    THE  STATE. 

and  creates  its  laws  and  institutions  in  accordance  with 

its  degree  oi'  progress  and  its  needs,  it  follows  that  the 

ends  for  which  the  State  exists  cannot  be  reached  by 

means   of   legal  institutions,   which   shall   embrace   the 

whole  human  race,  that  is,  by  one  universal  State,  but 

can   be   realized   only  in   a   multiplicity  of  States,   each 

possessing   its  own   sovereign   power   (cf.  supra,    §§    18, 

23,  33a). 

[Kant,  Bechtslehre.  Hegel,  Ecchtspliilosophie.  Schleier- 
macher,  Entvmrf  eines  Systems  der  Sittenlehre,  ed.  Schweizer, 
p.  274  f.  Zeh^e  vom  Staat.  Ueher  den  Beruf  des  Staates 
zur  Erziehung :  Werke,  zur  Fhilosophie,  vol.  iii.  p.  227  f. 
Christliche  Sitte,  pp.  241  f.,  440  f.  Eothe,  EthiJc,  2nd  ed. 
vol.  ii.  p.  204  f.  EncijMojxidic,  p.  83  f.  Chalybseus, 
Speculative  Mhik,  ii.  §  197  f.  Trendelenburg,  Naturreclit, 
§  150  f.  Stahl,  Rcchtsphilosophic,  ii.  2.  v.  Miihler,  Grundlinien 
einer  Fhilosophie  der  Staats-  und  Bechtslehre.  Herbart,  Prah- 
tische  Fhilosophie,  vol.  viii.,  cf.  also  vol.  ix.  Lotze,  Griindzuge 
der  praJdischen  Fhilosojyhie,  p.  60  f.  Ulrici,  Grundziige  der 
prahtischen  Fhilosophie,  i.  252  f,  J.  H.  Mchte,  Die  j^hiloso- 
2)hischen  Lehrcn  von  Recht,  Staat  und  Sitte.  Ihering,  Katnyf 
uriCs  Eecld.  Dahn,  Fcchtsphilosoj^hische  Studien,  p.  112  f. 
Lasson,  Sgstem  der  Fechtsphilosophie.  Baumann,  Handhuch  der 
Moral.  Schuppe,  Grundziige  der  Ethih.  Thiersch,  Ueher  den 
christlichen  Stacd,  1875.  Kostlin,  Staat,  Rccht  itnd  Kirche  in 
der  cvang.  Ethih.  Stitdien  uoid  KrUiken,  1877.  Gladstone,  The 
State  in  its  Relations  with  the  Church.  Coleridge,  Church  and 
StcUe.  Weisse,  Fhilosophische  Dogmatik,  iii.  pp.  617-654. 
Vinet,  Essai  sur  la  manifcstcdion  des  convictions  religieuses  et  sur 
la  separation  dc  Veglise  et  de  Pefat,  1842.  Zeller,  Staat  und 
Kirche.  IMinghetti,  Stacd  und  Kirche.  Geffken,  Stacd  und 
Kirche.  Thompson,  Church  and  StcUe  in  the  United  States. 
Herrmann,  Ueher  die  Stellung  der  Religionsgemeinschaften  im 
Staate.  Das  stacdliche  Veto  hci  Bischofswahlen.  Harless,  Stacd 
und  Kirche.  Beck,  Kirche  unci  Stacd  unci  ihr  Vcrhdltniss  zu 
cinandcr.  Vilmar,  Theologische  Moral,  vols.  ii.  and  iii.  v. 
Oettingen,  Christliche  Sittcnlehre,  p.  678  f.  Hofmann,  Theolo- 
gische Ethik,  p.  262  f.  Golther,  Staat  und  Kirche  im  Konig- 
rcich  Wilrtemhcrg.  Nippold,  Die  Theorie  der  Trennung  roii 
Kirche  und  Staat.  Sohm,  Verhdltniss  von  Staat  icnd  Kirche, 
1873.  Krauss,  Das  Dogma  von  der  unsichtharen  Kirche,  p. 
236  f.     Dorner,  Kirche  unci  Reich  Gottes,  p.  305  f  ] 

1.  Dependence  of  the  Stcde  upon  Religion.     We  have  already 


ITS  DEPENDENCE  UPON  PvELIGION.  557 

alluded  to  this  subject  (§  34ff,  of.  §  63.  2),  wlien  considering 
the  imperfection  of  the  stage  of  right  in  itself.  But  the 
dependence  of  the  State  upon  religion  is  shown  more  especially 
by  the  fact,  that  there  is  no  law,  no  earthly  power,  which  can 
exercise  control  or  afibrd  a  guarantee  against  the  abuse  of 
force,  except  Christian  conscientiousness  and  fidelity,  and 
Christian  respect  for  individual  freedom  and  individual  rights, 
alike  on  the  part  of  rulers,  officials,  and  the  people  at  large. 
Without  faith  in  a  living  Providence,  no  nation  can  success- 
fully meet  those  crises  in  its  political  life  which  cannot  fail  to 
arise,  or  pass  through  them  with  courage  and  patience,  with 
moderation  and  justice.  And  further,  legislation  also,  which 
always  bears  the  impress  of  the  whole  character  of  a  people, 
lacks  healthy  productive  power,  when  that  character  is  without 
religious  vitality  ;  for  then  the  nation  wants  that  ideal  element 
upon  which  the  formation  of  its  aims  depends.  It  is  this 
ideal  element  which  unites  rulers  and  subjects  by  inspiring 
them  with  a  common  spirit,  upheld  l;)y  enthusiasm  for  the 
discharge  of  national  duties. 

2.  Many  otherwise  right-thinking  Christians  would  fain 
regard  the  State  as  one  great  family,  and  the  monarch  as 
the  father  of  his  people.  It  is  certainly  in  favour  of  a 
monarchical  constitution,  that  it  imparts  to  the  State  some- 
what of  the  warmth  of  family  life.  But  the  State  is  not  a 
family.  This  is  shown,  e.rj.,  by  its  power  of  punishing ;  that 
which  is  discipline  in  the  family  is  punishment  in  the  State. 
The  State  may  go  so  far  in  this  respect  as  to  inflict  death. 
But  no  father  puts  his  child  to  death.  Here,  again,  the 
confounding  of  different  spheres  is  non-ethical.  And  this  is 
also  clear  from  the  consideration,  that  if  the  State  were  merely 
of  the  nature  of  a  family,  its  citizens  would  always  be  in  the 
position  of  children,  always  under  the  tutelage  of  the  ruling 
authorities.  But  the  latter  would  fulfil  its  educational  office 
very  badly,  if  citizens  were  kept  continually  in  the  condition 
of  minors.  The  State,  in  fact,  would  fall  into  the  same  error 
as  the  Eoman  Catholic  Church.  If,  however,  its  citizens  have 
passed  out  of  their  minority,  then  they  must  take  an  active 
part  in  political  life  and  in  the  discharge  of  its  principal 
functions.  Nor,  on  the  other  hand,  must  the  State  be  identified 
with  the    Church,    either   by   making   the   State   absorb   the 


558  §  75.    THE  STATE. 

CImrcli  or  vice  vcrsd.  Christianity  refuses  to  be  eitlier  a 
political  religion  or  a  theocracy.  Eender  unto  Csesar  the 
things  that  are  Caesar's ;  the  two  swords  must  be  kept 
separate.  There  is  certainly  an  intimate  connection  between 
these  two  divine  institutions,  but  their  functions  are  distinct, 
and  depend  upon  their  different  principles. 

The  principle  of  the  State  is  the  idea  of  Right.  This  does 
not  mean  that  the  State  is  the  sole  administrator  of  justice 
on  earth ;  justice  has  also  a  place  in  the  family  and  its 
discipline,  in  the  Church,  and  in  the  life  of  the  individual. 
But  it  administers  public  right,  and  has  to  enforce  it  by 
means  of  compulsion,  and  with  the  certainty  of  a  natural 
force  (§  33ft).  For  it  is  the  supreme  organism  so  far  as  right 
is  concerned ;  it  not  merely  exhibits  right,  but  it  is  the 
representative  of  right  raised  to  a  higher  power — that  is  to 
say,  not  merely  as  something  self-existent,  but  as  something 
that  is  active  and  self-determining.  It  has  to  manifest  right 
as  what  must  be  enforced  at  any  cost.  It  is  a  free  power, 
a  living  existence,  a  moral  personality  (§  33ft).  And  its 
position  with  regard  to  all  other  provinces  of  life  is,  that  it 
protects  each  of  them  in  the  rights  based  upon  its  respective 
ethical  principle,  that  it  embraces  them  all  as  an  institution 
for  the  maintenance  of  right.  The  State,  however,  is  by  no 
means  synonymous  with  the  entire  moral  activity  of  a  people, 
nor  is  it  lord  over  the  principles  belonging  to  the  other  moral 
spheres.  It  is  not  part  of  its  functions  to  n)ake  or  to  teach 
religion,  to  bring  about  marriages,  etc.  Neither  is  it  the  sum 
of  all  the  other  moral  communities  ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  itself 
one  of  them,  which  has  been  entrusted  with  the  administra- 
tion of  right,  in  virtue  of  which  it  must  ensure  to  them  all 
the  possibility  of  free  development,  in  accordance  with  the 
different  principles  underlying  them.  This  it  must  do  not 
only  negatively,  by  defending  them  from  outward  molestation, 
but  also  positively,  by  promoting  all  their  lawful  undertakings. 
Hence  it  is  incorrect  to  maintain,  that  too  little  has  been  said 
when  the  State  is  defined  as  being  based  on  the  idea  of  right, 
and  to  hold  that  it  must  also  care  for  the  public  welfare 
{i.e.  exercise  police  functions).  For  the  latter  duty  is  com- 
prehended in  the  idea  of  right  when  properly  conceived.  The 
State  represents  and  upholds  the  conditions  essential  to  the 


THE  IDEA.  OF  EIGHT.  559 

free  development  of  individual  life,  of  marriage  and  the 
family,  of  communities,  classes,  and  corporations,  whether  those 
whose  principle  is  realistic,  such  as  agriculture,  trade  and 
commerce,  or  of  those  whose  principle  is  ideal,  such  as  art 
and  science,  and  finally  of  the  Church  also.^  For  it  defends 
every  circle  of  human  life  from  anything  that  would  make 
its  free  development  impossible,  and  furnishes  it  with  that 
which  justly  belongs  to  it,  that  which  it  would  be  an  injustice 
to  refuse — viz.  the  means  by  which  its  free  development  is 
really  and  not  only  apparently  secured.  Accordingly,  the 
State  must  first  of  all  establish  its  own  rights,  its  rights  as  a 
State.  But  these  comprehend,  at  the  same  time,  the  rights 
of  all  other  spheres ;  and  all  rights,  both  those  which  the 
State  creates  (such  as  its  own)  and  those  which  it  recognises 
and  upholds  (such  as  the  rights  of  other  splieres),  have  a 
public  character.  Thus  there  arises  an  organized  system  of 
rights ;  and  there  are,  besides,  political  and  natural  rights, 
private  rights,  rights  of  the  family,  of  the  community,  of  trade 
and  commerce,  rights  belonging  to  science  (academies  and  the 
press),  to  art,  and  to  the  Church.  Hence  the  State,  as  the 
supreme  representative  of  right,  has  not  only  to  protect  the 
other  spheres  in  the  enjoyment  of  their  rights,  and  conse- 
quently to  set  limits  to  their  rights  as  against  each  other ; 
it  has  also  to  determine  the  rights  of  these  spheres  in  relation 
to  its  own,  and  therefore  it  must  be  master  in  its  own  house, 
and  fix  what  its  own  house  is,  and  how  far  its  domain 
extends.  In  doing  this  it  may,  of  course,  err ;  its  decision  is 
not  infallible  nor  incapable  of  amendment ;  still,  as  the  last 
and  highest  earthly  decision  in  all  matters  pertaining  to  right, 
it  must  be  honoured  by  obedience,"  or  if  this  would  violate 
clear  duties,  by  willingness  to  suffer. 

For  the  idea  of  right  establishes  the  Divine  origin  of  the 
State,  and  excludes  that  theory  of  it  according  to  wdiich  it  is 
based  originally  upon  contract  (Eousseau's  Contrat  Social). 
And  in  the  idea  of  right,  too,  we  have  the  inward  bond  that 
connects  the  State  with  religion.  For  right,  while  in  itself 
an  absolutely  necessary  good,  exists  for  the  sake  of  positive 

1  Hence  the  Apol,  ed.    Miiller,   p.    232,    designates    the   State   "defensor 
Evangelii." 
^  Conf,  Aug.  A.  xvi.     Apol.,  ed.  Miiller,  p.  225  f. 


560  §  75.    THE  STATE. 

morality.  The  State  derives  its  sovereignty  or  majesty  from 
the  fact,  that  it  simply  stands  security  for  right,  as  something 
public  and  national;  and  hence  it  recognises  no  power  superior 
to  itself. 

3.  The  difference  between  Ifaterial  and  Formal  Eight. 
Eight  attains  to  formal  perfection  when  it  takes  the  form  of 
law.  But  in  order  that  anything  like  arbitrariness — which, 
however  well-meaning  it  may  ]3e,  is  always  hurtful — may  be 
excluded,  it  is  first  of  all  necessary  that  there  should  he  a  lavj 
for  legislation.  Law  thus  raised  to  its  second  power  can 
only  be  realized  by  a  constitution  or  fundamental  law  of  the 
State. 

The  contents  of  right  vary  at  different  times  and  in  different 
places,  in  accordance  with  national  individuality.  That  which 
is  conducive  to  the  education  of  one  people,  and  promotes  its 
freedimi,  may  be  a  restriction  to  the  freedom  of  another  that 
is  more  matured ;  and  that  which  is  just  and  indispensable  in 
the  case  of  one  nation,  whose  life  has  reached  a  high  degi^ee 
of  development,  may  be  highly  injurious  to  another  which  is 
on  a  lower  level.  Human  laws  change  with  human  needs, 
and  a  contrast  is  often  presented  by  the  rights,  not  only  of 
different  peoples,  but  also  of  the  same  people  at  different 
stages  of  its  progress.  Material  right  has  a  history.  It  must 
grow  and  develop  so  as  to  meet  the  new  relations  that  are 
ever  arising,  and  which  it  must  regulate ;  and  laws  must  be 
reformed  or  purified  when  they  are  unjust,  or  are  in  danger 
of  becoming  so.  It  might,  indeed,  be  supposed  that  in  con- 
sequence of  these  changes  right  would  suffer  in  sureness  or 
stability.  But  the  continuity  of  right,  and  its  identity  as  an 
organized  whole,  are  maintained  when  the  development  and 
improvement  of  material  right  takes  place  in  a  way  that  is 
formally  correct — i.e.  through  the  legitimate  organs.  The 
old  strife  between  natural  right,  or  right  as  a  matter  of  reason, 
and  positive  right — a  strife  that  ever  and  anon  makes  itself 
felt  in  practical  life — cannot  be  brought  to  a  favourable  issue 
unless  the  two  following  facts  are  clearly  recognised.  On  the 
one  hand,  whenever  a  collision  arises  between  positive  right 
and  right  as  determined  by  reason,  the  former  is  shaken  to 
its  foundations  if  it  seeks  to  avoid  development  and  improve- 
ment ;  and,  on  the  other  hand,  a  legislative  reform  can  only 


POLITICS  AND  EELIGION.  561 

be  called  rational  when  it  can  be  shown  to  be  the  expression 
or  result^  of  the  general  sense  of  right  existing  in  the  com- 
munity at  the  time.  This  is  the  political  expression  of  the 
theological  principle  which  we  met  with  at  an  earlier  stage 
(§§  5,  72) :  the  coming  of  the  kingdom  of  God  depends  upon 
the  fact  that  it  has  already  come.  Stagnation  and  revolution 
must  be  alike  condemned.  The  right  thing  is  a  reforming 
conservatism.  This  is  no  special  political  banner ;  it  only 
describes  the  position  that  all  must  take  who  love  their 
country  truly  and  wisely.  All  Christian  citizens  must  enrol 
themselves  under  it,  however  much  they  may  differ  as  to  the 
expediency  of  concrete  political  questions,  by  which  they 
should  never  allow  themselves  to  be  separated. 

Politics  and  religion  must  not  be  mixed.  It  is  very 
dangerous  to  bring  in  religion  to  settle  concrete  political 
questions,  and  thus  to  make  them  religious  questions.  For 
by  this  means  political  parties  become  religious  parties  as 
well,  and  pride  is  the  result ;  the  political  fanatic  is  very  apt 
to  regard  an  opponent  as  a  non-Christian,  and  thus  religion 
is  defiled.  Further,  when  Christian  piety  is  identified  with 
a  particular  political  party,  the  mistrust  and  hatred,  that  are 
felt  towards  that  party  by  its  opponents,  are  turned  against 
religion  itself.  On  this  subject  the  Erlanger  Zcitschrift,  1862, 
makes  the  following  apt  observations  : — "  We  are  in  danger 
of  becoming  not  merely  political  perverts,  but  perverts  from 
Christianity,  if  we  seek  to  decide  political  questions,  such  as 
domiciliation,  right  of  suffrage,  finance  and  commerce,  the 
administration  of  justice,  trade,  the  legislature  and  popular 
representation  in  it,  etc.,  by  Christianity,  according  to  our 
measure  of  Christian  enlightenment.  For  then  we  suppose 
ourselves  all  the  better  Christians  because  we  take  up  a 
certain  position  in  politics,  and  we  think  we  have  a  right 
to  deny  the  Christianity  of  others  because  they  do  not  share 
our  political  views;  whereas  the  fact  is,  that  political  questions 

*  The  Legislature,  however,  must  not  simply  make  into  law  whatever  it  finds 
existing  as  custom ;  on  the  contrary,  it  may  oppose  a  prevailing  custom,  and 
acts  rightly  when  it  gathers  from  the  healthy  tendency  of  public  opinion,  to 
what  it  may  warrantably  give  the  formal  sanction  of  law.  It  is  only  necessary 
that  legislative  changes  should  be  in  accord  with  the  national  spirit,  and  the 
test  of  their  seasonableness  is  whether  the  national  spirit  is  reflected  in  them. 
If  not,  the  change  is  a  step  backward. 

2  N 


562  §  76.    CONTINUATION. 

must  be  judged  according  to  their  own  particular  principle, 
and  religion  gives  us  as  little  information  about  them  as  about 
the  best  way  of  making  any  kind  of  fabric.  Should  this 
tendency  gain  the  upper  hand,  especially  on  the  'part  of  the 
clergy,  then  tlie  sole  p)eaccinahing  'power  that  still  keeps  political 
parties  together,  inspiring  them  with  mutual  respect,  with  a 
sense  of  justice,  with  love  for  their  country — the  power,  namely, 
of  religion — would  he  drawn  tvithin  the  sphere  of  faction,  and 
the  salt  that  keeps  the  body  of  society  from  dissolution  would 
lose  its  savour." — Does  it  follow  from  this  that  the  Christian 
is  to  take  no  concern  in  the  public  affairs  of  his  country,  and 
to  form  no  political  opinions  at  all  ?  By  no  means.  But  he 
guards  himself  against  mixing  up  different  moral  spheres ; 
for  this  produces  a  chaos,  or  increases  the  chaos  that  exists. 
Love  to  one's  country  and  ones  people  has  received  the  blessing, 
not  only  of  Moses  (Ex.  xxxii.)  and  the  prophets,  but  also  of 
Christ  Himself.^  But  the  most  pious  man  is  not  necessarily 
the  best  versed  in  politics,  and  the  gospel  by  itself  settles 
nothing  with  regard  to  such  matters  as  a  political  constitution 
and  the  like.  Political  questions  have  their  own  independent 
principle,  and  must  be  decided  in  accordance  with  it. 
Christianity  simply  demands  of  all,  that  they  should  bring  their 
political  intelligence  to  bear  upon  such  questions  in  an  upright 
and  patriotic  spirit,  and  that  a  solution  should  be  arrived  at 
in  a  legitimate  way,  and  always  in  accordance  with  actual 
necessities  and  possibilities.  As  to  what  is  the  right  solution, 
different  views  may  be  held  by  people  who  are  equally  pious, 
and  these  differences  must  be  adjusted  by  friendly  contest 
and  discussion, 

§  76.   Continuation. 

Political  organization  begins  when  a  people  divides  itself  into 
a  magistracy  ^  (ObrigJceit)  on  the  one  hand,  and  subjects 
on  the  other.  But  this  contrast  between  rulers  and 
subjects,  without  which  a  people  would  be  merely  a 
uniform  mass,  destitute  of  organic  structure,  may  take 

'  Luke  xix.  41,  xxiii.  29  ;  cf.  Rom.  ix.  1  f. 

["The  "magistracy"  (Obrigkeit)  is  equivalent  to  the  "higher  powers"  of 
Eom.  xiii.  1,  and  includes  every  form  of  legally  constituted  authority. — Tk.] 


PUBLIC  RIGHT.  563 

very  different  forms.  Whatever  form  the  magistracy 
may  have,  obedience,  for  God's  sake  (Rom.  xiii.  1  f.),  is 
due  to  it  within  the  sphere  over  which  its  authority 
extends.  But  since  it  is  only  through  God  that  it  has 
a  claim  to  obedience,  it  cannot  make  that  claim  valid 
in  opposition  to  God  and  His  ordinances.  Thus  no 
obedience  is  to  be  rendered  it  which  would  involve 
disobedience  to  God ;  in  such  a  case,  however,  we  must 
recognise  the  inviolability  and  sanctity  of  lawful 
authority  by  being  willing  to  suffer. 

1.  Public  right  (§  75)  must  have  its  organs.  It  is  no 
doubt  true  that  in  a  certain  sense  all  citizens  are  its  organs 
(§  23,  33«);  but  this  cannot  possibly  mean  that  every 
individual  is  appointed  to  protect  others  from  himself,  or 
himself  from  the  whole  community.  In  such  a  case,  the 
very  thing  that  is  here  of  essential  importance — viz.  the 
community  as  a  whole  —  could  never  come  into  actual 
existence  or  manifestation.  It  is  the  State  which  is  the 
guardian  of  right,  not  the  individual  with  his  private  leanings, 
party  spirit  passions,  or  weak  pliability.  A  people  must 
therefore  divide  itself  into  vehicles  of  public  right  and  the 
force  it  employs,  and  those  who  are  subject  to  them. 
Obedience  to  the  State  becomes  obedience  to  those  who  are 
authorized  to  represent  the  State.  Thus  we  have  the 
antithesis  of  rulers  and  subjects.  Civil  authority  must  have 
persons  as  it  vehicles.  At  the  same  time,  however,  office  and 
person  are  not  simply  and  absolutely  coincident. 

2.  Here  it  is  not  of  importance  what  the  form  of  govern- 
ment may  be.  It  may  be  a  monarchy,  or  there  may  be  more 
rulers  than  one :  civil  power  may  be  regularly  divided 
between  a  prince  and  the  estates  of  the  realm,  or  the  latter 
may  at  least  assist  in  its  exercise ;  in  short,  civil  authority, 
where  it  really  exists — not  merely  when  it  seems  to  exist — 
must,  according  to  God's  ordinance,  require  obedience  within 
its  own  sphere.  Since  St.  Paul  (Ptom.  xiii.  1  f)  addresses  his 
demand  to  every  soul,  he  demands  at  the  same  time  that  every 
one  should  attach  himself  to  the  State.  For  the  individual 
does  so  by  becoming  subject  to  the  ruling  powers,  to  the  will 


564  '  §  76.    CONTINUATION. 

of  the  commonwealth  in  its  legally  constituted  form  [the 
authorities  being  the  representatives  of  the  commonwealth, 
and  for  that  reason  inseparably  allied  with  this  constitutional 
will  (§  75,  p.  55G  f.)].  The  king  also  who  is  called  to  the 
throne  in  the  order  of  succession,  in  the  very  act  of  ascending 
it  subjects  himself  to  this  general  will.  But  now,  what  is 
the  more  exact  meaning  of  Eom.  xiii.  If.?  Thus  far  all  are 
agreed,  viz.  that  we  are  here  commended  to  render  obedience 
to  civil  authority  as  an  ordinance  of  God.  The  apostle, 
after  previously  warning  us  against  taking  the  law  into  our 
own  hands  and  avenging  our  own  injuries,  says,  "  there  is  no 
power  but  of  God ;  and  the  powers  that  be  are  ordained  of 
God."  Here  the  first  clause  expresses  the  universal  principle, 
that  authority  in  general  derives  its  existence  from  God,  that 
it  has  no  lower  origin  than  this,  no  merely  physical,  or 
subjective,  human  origin.  The  second  repeats  this  in  a 
positive  form,  but  in  such  a  way  that  it  is  applied  to 
authorities  which  exist  in  concreto.  Each  one  of  them  must 
be  regarded  as  divinely  ordained  within  its  own  sphere,  and 
must  therefore  be  respected  as  such.  Here  St.  Paul  does  not 
say  what  persons  are,  in  any  particular  case,  to  be  regarded 
as  lawful  rulers,  and  therefore  as  ordained  by  God ;  he  does 
not  enter  into  this  question  at  all,  but  is  occupied  solely  with 
the  institution.  '  Hence  he  makes  no  distinction  between  bad 
and  good  rulers ;  for  the  institution  itself  is  always  good,  it 
is  only  the  persons  who  are  not  always  good.  Still  his  words 
involve  that  obedience  must  be  cheerfully  given  to  the 
persons  also,  inasmuch  and  in  so  far  as  they  are  lawful 
authorities,  that  is  to  say,  in  so  far  as  the  person  and  the 
of&ce  or  institution  are  one.  It  is  said  by  some  that  St.  Paul 
does  not  merely  tell  us  what  belongs  to  the  ruling  powers  as  an 
institution,  but  also  how  such  powers  may  be  recognised,  namely, 
by  their  virepex^iv.  But  if  the  sure  mark  of  lawful  authority 
were  to  be  found  in  virepe'x^eiv,  that  is,  if  might  ^  were  the 
sole  means  whereby  we  discover  who  are  Divinely  -  ordained 
authorities,  then  St.  Paul  would  say — what  he  undoubtedly 

'  Might  is  not  the  same  as  right,  as  is  maintained  in  the  preface  of  the  Evan- 
gelische  Kirchenzeitung,  1851.  According  to  the  theory  of  Hengstenberg,  a 
successful  revolution  would  at  once  have  the  right  to  be  regarded  as  a  divinely- 
appointed  ruling  power. 


"  THE  POWEES  THAT  BE."  5 Go 

cannot  say — that  we  have  simply  to  obey  the  power  which 
happens  at  any  time  to  be  in  the  ascendant.  He  says,  on  the 
contrary,  the  powers  set  over  us.  Who  these  are  it  is  easy 
in  ordinary  times  to  say,  but  when  extraordinary  circum- 
stances arise,  it  is  hard  and  even  impossible  to  determine  this 
thoroughly,  since  in  that  case  it  depends  upon  concrete 
relations.  An  especial  difficulty  also  arises  from  the  fact, 
that  just  as  something  which  at  first  was  unjustly  acquired 
may  through  length  of  time  become  lawful  property,  so  a 
land  which  was  seized  and  subdued  by  force,  to  begin  with, 
may  by  and  by  be  rightfully  held,  and  lawful  authority 
established  within  it.  Now,  while  it  is  certainly  true  that 
the  Christian  must  not  assist  in  depriving  his  lawful  rulers 
of  their  power,  while,  on  the  contrary,  it  is  his  duty  to  remain 
loyal  to  them,^  yet  he  must  not  at  such  great  political  crises 
as  we  are  speaking  of,  interfere  arbitrarily  and  in  his  indi- 
vidual capacity ;  whether  in  the  way  of  offering  armed 
resistance,  or  of  taking  an  active  public  part  in  favour  of 
legitimacy.  The  matter  at  issue  being  one  of  universal 
interest,  he  must  leave  it,  in  the  first  place,  to  the 
cqjpointecl  ixpresentativcs  of  the  people  (see  below,  §  77.  2), 
and  content  himself  with  abstaining  from  committing  any 
injustice.'  Further,  when  a  new  governing  power  displaces 
an  old  one,  it  is,  on  the  one  hand,  incumbent  on  the  former 
to  respect  the  old  bonds  of  duty,  and  not  to  demand  any  oath 
of  allegiance  or  of  office,  until  the  struggle  has  been  brought 

^  We  may  liere  allude  to  those  who  use  the  name  of  Paul  as  a  cloak  for 
disloyalt}'.  After  having  given  an  oath  of  fidelity  to  their  ancestral  prince, 
should  he  happen  to  be  overcome  for  a  while  by  his  enemies,  and  should  rebels 
or  aliens  demand  that  an  oath  of  fidelity  should  be  given  to  them,  these  persons 
readily  give  it, — it  may  be  under  the  pretext  that  the  enemies  of  their  own 
prince  would  never  have  become  possessed  of  this  power,  had  it  not  been  given 
them  from  above  (John  xix.  11),  that  their  power  is  the  decision  of  God.  In 
certain  circumstances  it  is  no  doubt  a  convenient  doctrine  to  yield  to  might 
instead  of  right,  and  to  regard  those  persons  who  have  the  power  as  its 
lawful  possessors.  But  should  any  one,  from  cowardice  or  selfishness,  or  from 
essential  contempt  of  the  State,  hold  it  to  be  a  proper  thing  to  swim  with  the 
tide  of  power  on  every  occasion,  he  must  not  make  the  apostle  his  companion 
and  adviser  in  disloyalty. 

"  [We  can  hardly  believe  that  the  author  means  to  exclude  attempts  to 
influence  public  opinion  within  legitimate  limits,  since  he  demands  publicity 
and  free  discussion  as  essential  to  free  political  life.  §  77.  2,  §  78,  §  70.  2. 
— Ed.J 


566  §  76.    CONTINUATION. 

to  a  definite  close ;  while,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  right  that 
when    once   a  final    issue    has    been    reached,   the    outgoing 

^  DO 

government  should  release  the  consciences  of  its  subjects  from 
their  obligations.  For  a  country  must  have  a  civil  authority. 
Eulers  exist  for  the  sake  of  the  institution.  In  such  cases 
much  will  always  have  to  be  left  to  the  judgment  of  the 
Christian  conscience,  since  decisive  marks,  suitable  to  all 
cases,  cannot  be  given  to  enable  us  to  determine  who  still 
are  or  who  have  become  the  i^ovaia.  But  what  shall  we 
say  with  regard  to  political  commotions  within  the  same 
nation  ?  Here,  too,  St.  Paul  cannot  mean  that  the  e^ovaia  has 
a  claim  to  obedience ;  only  if  at  the  same  time  it  has  superior 
power,  and  that  when  it  has  not  the  power  it  has  not  the 
claim.  He  would  not  say,  for.  example,  that  in  a  time  of 
revolution  we  should  abandon  a  lawful  dynasty  and  authority, 
and  go  over  to  the  side  of  revolution,  should  the  latter  be 
stronger  than  the  former.  The  apostle  has  no  idea  of 
teaching  us  to  swim  with  the  tide  of  power ;  it  is  lawful 
authority  that  is  in  his  mind ;  to  this,  and  in  so  far  as  it  is 
lawful,  our  obedience  is  due. 

We  thus  see  that  St.  Paul's  object  is  not  to  exalt  certain 
definite  persons,  but  to  commend  civil  authority  as  a  beneficial 
institution  ordained  by  God.  For  this  reason  we  never  find 
him  saying,  that  those  who  have  the  potver  have  also  on  that 
account  the  Divine  right  to  demand  obedience,  even  should 
they  shatter  the  basis  of  right  upon  which  their  authority 
rests;  on  the  contrary,  he  says  that  where  there  is  true  civil 
authority,  —  and  therefore  not  merely  a  power  that  may 
become  so  in  the  future,  or  has  been  so  in  the  past,  or  seems 
to  be  so  now,  but  a  power  that  is  lawfully  authoritative  at 
the  present  moment, — such  authority  must  be  honoured  as 
an  ordinance  of  God.  The  persons  who  fill  the  office  may 
possibly  act  m  opposition  to  the  institution  or  office  which 
has  divine  authority.  Now,  should  it  be  said,  that  in  such  a 
separation  of  office  and  person  it  is  nevertheless  that  which 
is  accidental,  viz.  the  person,  and  not  the  permanent  Divine 
office,  which,  according  to  the  apostle,  must  be  emphasized, 
this  would  mean,  that  whoever  is  disobedient  to  the  person, 
in  order  to  obey  the  office  which  is  God's  ordinance,  would 
resist  God's  ordinance    by  obeying  it.     In  Acts  iv.   19  the 


CHEISTIAN  OBEDIENCE  TO  AUTHORITY.  567 

necessary  distinction  is  made  between  the  persons  who,  either 
in  general  or  in  any  particular  instance,  claim  to  have  ruling 
authority,  and  the  office.  St.  Peter  asserts  the  possibility  of 
separating  between  office  and  person  when  he  says,  not  that 
we  ought  to  obey  God  rather  than  the  authorities,  but — 
rather  than  "  men."  Obedience  is  always  due  to  lawful 
authority ;  it  is  always  an  ordinance  of  God ;  for  the 
administration  of  justice  is  its  divine  right  as  well  as  its 
divine  duty.  But  the  person,  who  enjoins  something  that 
is  opposed  to  God  and  divine  law,  only  seems  in  such  an 
act  to  be  a  legitimate  authority,  authorized  by  God ;  in 
reality  it  is  only  the  unworthy  human  being  and  not  the 
office  that  demands  the  sin  ;  and  hence  what  is  commanded 
is  not  binding.  So  with  regard  to  Matt.  xxii.  15  f.  The 
two  things  are  quite  compatible, — although  the  Pharisees  and 
theocrats  did  not  think  so, — to  render  unto  Csesar  the  things 
wliich  are  Ceesar's,  and  unto  God  the  things  that  are  God's, 
because  civil  authority  has  no  rights  that  are  opposed  to  God, 
but  derives  all  its  rights  from  Him.  Christians  do  not  obey 
their  rulers  blindly,  but  consciously,  conscientiously,  and  for 
that  reason  all  the  more  earnestly.  By  consciously  we  mean 
that  when  they  obey  they  are  certain  of  the  magisterial 
position  of  their  rulers,  certain,  too,  with  regard  to  what 
is  commanded  that  it  is  not  opposed  to  God  or  conscience. 
And  this  holds  good  not  merely  in  directly  religious, 
but  also  in  moral  matters.  Christian  obedience  to  lawful 
authority  is  not  a  mere  obedience  from  fear  of  punish- 
ment, but  is  given  for  God's  sake,  because  the  Christian 
knows  that  God  has  appointed  civil  government  upon  earth 
(1  Pet.  ii.  13  ;  Eom.  xiii.  5).  Hence  he  obeys  joyfully  and 
willingly,  as  an  act  of  worship  rendered  to  God ;  even  should 
the  sacrifice  be  hard,  it  is  still  a  sacrifice  laid  upon  God's 
altar  (Eom.  xiii.  6). 

In  short,  the  'persons  who  exercise  magisterial  functions 
have  to  demand  obedience  on  behalf  of  their  office — in  its 
formal  aspect,  because  it  has  been  instituted  by  God,  in  its 
material  aspect,  because  of  its  aim,  which  is  justice.  Hence 
it  follows  as  a  matter  of  course — 

{a)  That  the  Christian  is  bound  to  refuse  compliance  with 
every  ungodly  requisition,  every  invitation  to  do  what  is  sinful, 


568  §  77.    CONTINUATION. 

as,  for  example,  to  violate  the  rights  of  others,  even  should  it 
come  from  the  ruling  powers. 

(b)  That  as  long  as  rulers  continue  to  be  rulers,  that  is,  as 
long  as  they  do  not  overturn  altogether  that  general  basis  of 
rigid  upon  which  their  authority  rests,  they  must  be  obeyed 
within  their  own  sphere,  even  though  in  many  instances  they 
may  act  unjustly.  In  the  latter  case  the  Christian  must  submit 
to  the  injustice.  When  resistance  is  offered,  its  purpose 
must  never  be  more  than  defensive — to  defend  Right.  Eulers 
must  not  suffer  injury  within  their  legitimate  sphere;  we 
must  not  go  the  length  of  attacking  the  right  which  belongs 
to  them  [the  right,  namely,  which  rulers  in  general  possess, 
of  demanding  obedience  as  long  as  they  still  retain  lawful 
authority]. 

(c)  Should,  however,  a  ruler  resolve  to  have  nothing  more 
to  do  with  right  at  all,  but  to  act  entirely  from  his  own 
caprice,  he  would  himself  sever  the  bond  which  connects  the 
person  with  the  office  as  a  divine  institution,  and  which  gives 
to  the  former  a  share  of  the  sanctity  of  the  latter.  And  this 
would  be  equivalent  to  an  abdication  and  revolution.  The 
conservative  spirit  of  the  Christian,  his  zeal  for  the  main- 
tenance of  the  State,  would  have  to  react  against  such  a 
revolutionary  change ;  and  that  for  the  very  same  reasons 
which  make  it  a  divine  duty  to  found  a  State,  and  to  bring 
chaos  and  caprice  to  an  end  by  the  establishment  of  law. 
But,  on  the  other  hand,  until  such  an  extreme  crisis  has 
occurred  and  is  plainly  manifest,  neither  individuals  nor 
communities — whether  from  a  nitre  wish  to  escape  suffering, 
or  from  an  arrogant  but  false  desire  for  freedom — must  presume 
to  rise  in  rebellion,  and  attack  the  Divinely  ordained  autho- 
rities that  are  still  in  power,  even  should  these  often  act  in  a 
way  that  is  a  caricature  of  justice. 

§  77.   Contimiation. 

TJie  Constitution. 

The  system  which  regulates  the  relations  subsisting  between 
rulers  and  subjects  is  the  Constitution.  There  is  no 
constitution  that  is  the  best  absolutely ;  it  can  only  be 


THE  CONSTITUTIOK  569 

relatively  the  best,  according  to  the  individuality  of  a 
people,  and  the  stage  of  progress  it  has  reached  (§  75.  3). 
Nevertheless  it  may  be  said,  that  a  despotic  relation 
between  rulers  and  subjects,  in  the  form  either  of 
Ciesarism  or  ochlocracy,  is  as  little  in  harmony  with 
the  Christian  spirit  as  anarchy.  Christianity  favours, 
although  only  indirectly,  and  not  by  positive  precept,  a 
political  system  in  which  the  object  is  not  to  secure 
mere  passive  obedience,  but  also  to  give  citizens  an 
active  participation  in  State  affairs.  The  essential 
functions  of  the  State  as  an  organized  political  body,  or 
the  forms  in  which  it  exercises  its  authority,  are,  on  the 
ideal  side,  legislation,  and  on  the  real,  administration 
and  the  dispensation  of  justice.  When  a  people  takes 
a  positive  part  in  political  work,  by  means  of  those 
persons  to  whom  it  has  confided  its  interests,  the  latter, 
in  this  case,  form  a  part  of  a  composite  government, 
and  laws  which  are  passed  by  both  parts  are  binding 
upon  all. 

1.  There  has  been  much  discussion,  especially  from  the 
standpoint  of  natural  right,  as  to  what  is  the  best  form  of 
constitution.  But  this  is  a  question  which  cannot  be  answered 
a  priori,  nor  is  it  answered  by  Christianity.  It  is  part  of  the 
elasticity  of  Christianity,  that  it  can  maintain  itself  under  any 
kind  of  constitution.  The  history  and  individuality  of  a 
people  must  here  be  considered,  and  therefore  one  and  the 
same  constitution  cannot  be  the  best  for  every  people  and  for 
every  stage  of  progress.  Christianity,  too,  prescribes  no  par- 
ticular form.  It  only  lays  down  principles,  which  when 
followed,  overcome,  in  an  immanent  way  and  without  force, 
certain  gross  imperfections  or  ruder  forms  of  political  life. 
Now  this  must  be  said  in  general :  that  the  spirit  of  Chris- 
tianity, and  especially  of  the  evangelical  Church,  which  aims 
at  the  full  development  of  personality,  is  altogether  adverse 
to  every  political  system  which  looks  for  mere  passive  obe- 
dience on  the  part  of  its  subjects,  and  is  favourable  only  to  a 
system  which  admits  of  citizens  taking,  at  all  events  indirectly, 


570  §  77.    CONTINUATION,      DEMOCRACY, 

an  active  moral  part  in  political  affairs.  And  this  does  not 
mean  only  that  they  are  to  obey  freely  according  to  their  con- 
science, but  also  to  work  freely.  For  the  love  of  the  Christian 
embraces  his  earthly  fatherland  also. 

Now  when  we  compare,  from  this  point  of  view,  the  three 
chief  forms  of  political  constitution,  viz.  democracy,  aristo- 
cracy, and  monarchy,  we  must  remember — what  the  history 
of  ancient  nations  has  shown  us — that  a  nation  passes  through 
different  forms  of  constitution,  and  that  each  of  these  may  be 
the  best  for  its  own  age.  But  whereas  in  antiquity  one 
system  merely  overturned  and  abolished  another,  the  Cliristian 
era  exhibits  the  effort  to  interweave  with  one  another,  the 
elements  of  truth  which  each  of  these  systems  contains. 

(a)  The  trutli  in  the  idea  of  Democracy  is,  that  it  desires  to 
have  active  citizens,  swayed  by  the  idea  of  the  State.  But  the 
democratic  constitution  is  optimistic,  and  the  most  elementary 
of  all.  The  talent  of  the  statesman  is  a  special  gift,  not  a 
universal  one ;  yet  the  democratic  theory  speaks  and  acts  as 
if  every  citizen  could  be,  or  had  to  be,  politically  active  in  a 
productive  sense,  as  if  politics  were  not  an  art.  Productive 
action  in  politics  is  not  of  such  a  nature,  that  if  a  man  had  no 
share  in  it  he  would  be  excluded  from  a  good  of  absolute 
worth.  But  the  democratic  view  runs  the  risk  of  making  it 
an  absolute  good.  Further,  democracy  contains  much  that  is 
mere  appearance ;  for  in  reality  it  is  not  all  who  govern, 
but  mostly  demagogues,  who  push  themselves  to  the  front  by 
flattering  the  people.  Democracy  has  almost  no  means  of 
guarding  against  that  which  is  the  greatest  evil  in  every 
sphere,  namely,  that  those  who  are  inwardly  the  most  com- 
petent for  an  office  are  excluded  from  it  by  ostracism  of 
various  kinds,  while  those  who  are  incompetent  receive  it. 
Further,  democracy  has  then  become  immoral  when  it  makes 
ruling  and  the  right  to  rule,  not  the  rule  of  objective  right  or 
duty,  the  important  thing.  It  is  more  apt  than  any  other 
kind  of  government  to  cast  into  the  shade  the  moral  order  of 
the  State  as  a  Divine  institution,  and  the  Divine  right  of 
constituted  authority.  Moreover,  wdien  a  democratic  form 
of  government  is  not  confined  to  a  single  city,  but  extends 
over  a  whole  country,  a  pure  democracy  is  a  physical  impos- 
sibility, because  each  one  cannot  directly  take  part  in  govern- 


ARISTOCRACY,  MONAKCRY.  571 

ment  and  legislation.  Elections  must  be  held,  and  in  tliese 
there  is  the  introduction  of  an  aristocratic  element.  Were 
democracy  not  modified  by  aristocratic  elements,  it  would  lead 
to  ochlocracy. 

(&)  Aristocracy  has  also  its  special  advantages ;  also,  but  in 
a  less  degree,  plutocracy,  which,  in  North  America,  and  to 
some  extent  in  Europe,  has  displaced  nobility  of  birth,  or 
exists  together  with  the  latter.  Nobility  of  culture,  of 
character,  and  of  intelligence  will,  thank  God,  always  remain 
and  assert  its  truly  influential  position.  But  aristocratic 
constitutions  have  exhibited  as  little  permanence  as  demo- 
cratic ;  they  are  themselves  specially  accessible  to  a  narroio 
and  often  selfish  spirit  of  caste. 

(c)  A  Monarchic  constitution  is  without  doubt  much  more 
capable,  than  a  democratic  or  aristocratic  one,  of  maintaining 
the  continuity  of  the  State,  and  therewith  its  stability.  It  is 
likewise  most  in  harmony  with  the  idea  of  government.  For 
the  Homeric  eh  Koipavo<i  earco  holds  good  of  the  executive. 

Hcrcclitary  monarchy  is  preferable  to  elective  monarchy ; 
witness  the  experience  of  Poland,  and  also  of  Germany  in  its 
imperial  times.  The  hereditary  principle  raises  the  posses- 
sion of  sovereign  power  above  rivalry  and  ambition  within 
the  State,  above  dangerous  conflicts  and  civil  wars.  A  here- 
ditary dynasty  also  gives  rise  to  a  healthy  tradition,  which 
serves  to  secure  continuity  in  politics ;  it  enables  love  to  the 
State  to  take  root  more  easily  in  the  hearts  of  the  people,  who, 
by  seeing  in  the  prince  the  representative  of  the  State,  gain  a 
firmer  sense  of  the  objective  reality  of  the  State  and  its  laws. 
The  hereditariness  of  its  monarchy,  moreover,  procures  for  a 
State  the  blessing  of  family  affection,  somewhat  of  the  warmth 
of  family  life — so  far,  that  is,  as  the  idea  of  the  State  permits. 
This  is  a  benefit  which  republics,  whatever  form  they  may 
take,  cannot  obtain.  We  must,  however,  distinguish  between 
a  monarchy  and  a  clesjyotisyn,  in  the  latter  of  which  even  judi- 
cial power  is  dependent  upon  the  arbitrary  will  of  the  ruler. 
But  more  than  this  is  required  to  correspond  to  the  ethos  of 
the  State ;  it  is  not  enough  that  those  who  exercise  judicial 
functions  should  be  unbiassed  and   independent.     For  there 

•  In  Prussia,  courts  of  justice  were  independent,  even  before  1S48,  and  hence 
the  Government  was  not  a  despotism. 


572       §  77.    CONTINUATION.       CONSTITUTIONAL  MONAP.CHY. 

cannot  be  an  independent  administration  of  justice,  if  the 
legislative  power  could  lay  down,  perhaps  arbitrarily,  rules  to 
regulate  the  proceedings  of  the  law  courts.  Further,  since 
legislation  must  be  constantly  carried  on,  and  must  proceed 
from  the  real,  manifest  needs  of  the  people, — not  from  any 
extraneous  or  external  source,  whether  it  call  itself  human  or 
Divine  (§  75), — it  follows  as  a  matter  of  course,  that  the  mind 
of  the  people  must  enter  into  and  take  a  share  in  the  con- 
struction of  the  laws.  Not  even  the  appearance  of  a  merely 
individual  origin  must  attacli  to  laios. 

2.  Since  Eight,  for  the  sake  of  which  the  State  exists,  only 
reaches  its  perfect  shape  in  the  form  of  law  (§  75),  legislation 
is  the  fundamental  function  of  tlie  State,  and  hence  a  law  is 
required  to  regulate  legislation,  a  fundamental  latv  of  the  State 
(§  ^^'  PP-  ^^^:  556).  This  law  is  the  constitution,  in  the 
narrower  sense  of  the  term.  A  republic,  oio  less  than  a 
monarchy,  requires  a  constitution.  But  a  republic  is  not  so 
well  adapted  cas  a  monarchy  to  overcome  any  disorders  that 
arise,  and  it  is  especially  liable  to  fall  into  one  of  two  extremes, 
both  hostile  to  freedom,  anarcliy  and  the  absolutism  of  cen- 
tralization. In  both  of  these  respects  a  constitutional  monarchy 
is  superior.^  Accordingly,  when  a  people  is  under  a  monarchy, 
and  has  a  share  in  the  work  of  legislation  secured  to  it  by 
constitutional  law,  the  form  of  the  State  has  reached  that 
stage  which  is  as  yet  the  highest. 

Legislation  must  be  the  work  of  the  people  in  common — 
that  is,  of  that  part  of  the  nation  which  possesses  rights,  or  is 
of  age.  For  only  then  has  law  an  origin  corresponding  to  its 
significance  as  a  public  legal  ordinance,  with  which  the  people 
has  to  familiarize  itself,  or  in  which  it  has,  as  it  were,  to  feel 
at  home.  Law  must  proceed  from  those  for  whose  sake  it 
exists,  of  course  from  their  true  better  nature  or  sense  of  right. 
Now,  it  is  just  as  much  a  moral  perversion  to  understand  by 
the  people  only  those  who  are  governed,  and  to  regard  the 
Government  as  opposed  to  or  restricting  them,  as,  on  the  other 
hand,  it  is  to  look  upon  the  State  as  consisting  entirely  of  the 

^  The  principal  advantage  of  the  monarchic  fo  ni  of  constitution  is  its  elas- 
ticity, which  enables  it  to  forbid  its  framework,  to  exclude  any  beneficial 
elements  to  be  found  in  other  possible  constitutions,  but  to  appropriate  them 
and  incorporate  them  in  itself. 


LEGISLATION.  573 

Government  or  those  in  office.  It  is  those  who  govern  and 
those  who  are  governed  taken  together  that  constitute  the 
people,  and  reveal  the  true  mind  of  the  people.  Hence  it 
follows — {a)  that  those  who  are  governed  should  have  a  shai^e 
in  legislation,  and  it  is  a  lavj  of  legislation  that  this  share 
should  he  used,  that  no  law  should  have  legal  force  unless 
they  give  it  their  consent  through  their  representatives  (that  is, 
it  must  receive  the  consent  of  the  Chamber  of  Eepresentatives). 
ih)  Moreover,  since  the  Government,  too,  is  a  part  of  the 
people,  it  must  also  be  demanded  that,  as  being  the  natural 
representative  of  the  existing  order  of  things,  and  of  the  stability 
of  the  State,  it  should  not  merely  have  a  deliberative  voice 
in  legislation,  but  should  give  its  free  consent  to  the  enact- 
ment of  laws,  and  that  there  should  not  be  the  possibility  of 
outvoting  it.  Accordingly,  the  idea  of  a  merely  suspensive 
veto  on  the  part  of  the  Government  must  be  condemned.  It 
has  a  right  to  an  absolute  veto,  and  this  the  Chambers  also 
have  with  reference  to  the  proposals  of  the  Government.  Like- 
wise, it  must  never  come  to  pass  tliat  the  majority  should 
tyrannize  over  the  minority,  nor  that  all  the  distinctions  which 
exist  within  the  nation  should  be  obliterated,  that  all  the 
organic  combinations  which  men  have  formed  with  each  other 
should  be  destroyed  by  bringing  every  one  to  the  same  level 
of  abstract  equality.  On  the  contrary,  a  State  only  attains  to 
fresh  and  vigorous  life,  and  a  people  to  actual  freedom,  when 
the  latter  exhibits  an  abundant  variety  of  organized  bodies, 
which  are  in  their  turns  members  of  the  greater  organism,  the 
State,  and  each  of  which,  ivhile  resting  upon  a  natural  hasis,  is 
nevertheless  a  moral  prodiict,  e.g.  Communes,  Districts,  Provinces, 
and,  the  Glasses.  In  the  abolition  of  the  old  class  distinctions 
there  is  a  genuine  moral  idea,  viz.  that  there  are  no  longer  to 
be  merely  physical  classes,  to  which  a  man  belongs  at  once  by 
birth,  but  only  ethical,  that  is,  classes  with  a  physical  basis 
indeed  (§  17),  but  formed  by  actual  work,  and  by  morally 
justifiable  interests.  There  are  therefore  to  be  no  castes,  no 
nobility  in  the  old  sense  of  the  word.  If  the  nobility  can 
become  ethical,^  if  they  can  point  to  some  special  worh,  which 
from   the  physical   advantages  of   their  order  they  are  best 

'  As,  for  example,  in  England,  where  nobility  of  birth  does  not  necessarily 
ekvate  a  man  to  the  rank  of  nobleman. 


5V'l  §  77.    CONTINUATION,      LEGISLATION, 

qualified  to  perform  for  the  general  welfare/  tlieu  ethics  can 
have  nothing  to  say  against  them.  But  there  must  be  uo 
class  whose  only  work  is  enjoyment.  The  mere  negation, 
however,  of  the  old  class  distinctions  is  just  as  pernicious  as 
these  distinctions  themselves,  unless  something  higher  be  put 
in  their  place.  A  reorganization  of  classes,  communes,  corpora- 
tions, and  guilds  is  necessary  for  the  State  in  general,  but 
especially  with  regard  to  the  social  question. 

It  is  probable,  too,  that  such  a  reorganization  alone  affords 
a  way  to  the  right  solution  of  the  problem,  as  to  how  a  true 
representation  of  the  governed  classes  is  to  be  contrived.  For 
every  one  must  be  excluded,  who  cannot  give  an  adequate 
guarantee  that  he  is  an  actual,  living  member  of  the  State. 
A  census  is  insufficient ;  the  timocracy  which  it  implies  has 
something  lowering  about  it,  since  it  makes  the  idea  of  the 
State  depend  upon  wealth  ;  it  is  a  makeshift,  although  the 
payment  of  taxes  must  remain  a  condition  of  the  enjoyment 
of  political  rights.  But  most  of  all,  it  is  only  by  a  regenera- 
tion of  guilds  and  the  like,  that  class  -  honour  and  class- 
usages  can  arise,  or  that  the  respective  classes  can  again  each 
win  a  fixed  place  in  the  social  organism,  without  which  they 
have  neither  centre  nor  support.  One  of  the  most  important 
duties  of  the  State  is  to  see  that  there  is  no  mere  rabble  in 
the  community,  no  proletariat.  In  all  classes  the  proletariat 
has  its  members  and  candidates.  Its  essential  character  is 
moral  disconnection,  the  want  of  a  definite  relation  to  society, 
due  to  the  lack  of  an  organization  including  all  classes.  It 
has  indeed  its  peculiar  seat  among  the  poorer  classes.  It  is 
pauperism  that  makes  the  proletariat  so  dangerous  (cf.  §  63). 
It  is  true  that  all  must  form  the  material,  the  component  parts 
of  the  public  community,  which  the  idea  of  Eight  calls  into 
existence.  But  these  countless  atoms  must  be  organized  by 
means  of  their  vocations  (§  68),  or  the  classes  to  which  they 
belong.  For  all  must  have  an  ethical  basis,  they  must  have 
duties  and  hence  rights  (§  23).  Such  questions,  we  may  also 
observe,  always  show  the  limits  of  the  power  of  the  State,  its 
dependence  upon  other  potencies,  without  which  it  cannot 
cope  with  the  dangers  that  threaten  its  life  (§  34a,  §  75.  1). 
3.  Legislation  is  the  ideal  side  of  the  functions  of  the 
'  E.g.  Court  duties,  ambassadorships,  and  to  some  extent  military  offices. 


ADMINISTRATION.  575 

State ;  it  determines  the  aims  to  be  pursued,  and  in  so  doing 
requires  to  be  guided  by  creative  love  and  wisdom.  The  real 
side  of  the  State  functions  is  administroJion,  in  the  wider 
sense.  Here  its  principal  task  is  to  carry  out  and  enforce 
the  laws  themselves,  or  public  right.  This  demands  wisdom, 
technical  skill,  and  power.  Administration  must  be  carried 
on  in  accordance  with  law,  and  hence  comes  itself  within  the 
sphere  of  legislation.  Not  that  legislation  and  administration 
must  be  confounded  with  one  another,  but  their  legitimate 
relations  must  be  defined  by  constitutional  law. 

Further,  the  laws  and  ordinances  of  civil  and  political  life 
— the  administration  of  which  is  the  first  duty  of  the  State 
— must  also  be  maintained  and  put  into  execution  against 
the  disturbances  and  injuries  occasioned  by  wrongdoing,  and 
this  without  respect  of  persons  and  in  the  case  of  both  the 
highest  and  the  lowest.  Hence  the  administration  of  justice 
must  necessarily  be  made  independent  of  administration  in 
the  narrower  sense,  and  thus  this  real  side  itself  falls  into  the 
divisions  known  as  the  administrative,  the  executive,  and  the 
judicial  functions. 

The  function  of  administration  in  the  narrower  sense 
belongs  to  the  Government,  and  is  again  divided  into  different 
branches.  But  since  it  must  be  carried  on  in  accordance 
with  the  law,  it  follows  that  the  classes,  which  take  a  share 
in  the  formation  of  the  laws,  exercise  a  controlling  influence 
over  the  Government,  without,  however,  forming  a  superior 
court  over  it,  since  this  would  make  the  Government  sub- 
ordinate to  them.  Publicity  is  essential  to  free  political  life. 
Since  laws  are  made  that  they  may  be  put  in  force,  the  organs 
of  the  Government  (through  whom,  under  a  monarchy,  the 
ruler  acts)  are  responsible  for  their  execution.  The  king  is 
not  responsible,  nor  are  the  classes.  Hence  the  king's 
Government  also  must  be  so  composed  as  to  be  in  general 
harmony  with  the  people.  To  meet  the  case  of  incurable 
divisions  arising  between  the  Government  and  the  represen- 
tatives of  the  people,  there  must  be  a  su'preme  court  inde- 
pendent of  hoth  parties,  to  settle  the  matters  in  dispute,  and 
thus  obviate  any  revolutionary  action  from  the  one  side  or 
the  other. 

4.  Judicial   Functions.       As   the   judicial    functions    of  a 


576  §  77.    CONTINUATION.       CAPITAL  PUNISHMENT. 

State  must  necessarily  be  independent  of  the  administration, 
so  too  they  must  have  one  source.  This  comes  out  in  courts  of 
appeal.  Judicial  decisions  are  a  prerogative  of  the  State,  and 
hence  in  monarchies  they  are  rightly  given  in  the  name  of 
the  king,  although  it  is  quite  possible  that  they  may  be 
against  the  king  (witness  the  miller  of  Sans  -  Souci  and 
Frederick  II.).  In  the  administration  of  justice  also,  publicity 
is  essential  to  free  national  life.  Trial  by  jury  is  a  good  thing 
in  itself;  but  it  can  only  be  attended  with  beneficial  results, 
when  a  courageous  and  impartial  sense  of  right  is  widely 
diffused  among  all  classes.  With  regard  to  the  right  of 
administering  penal  j\isticc,  we  have  seen  in  §  33a  the  moral 
grounds  on  which  it  is  based.  But  the  question  still  remains 
— ought  capital  punishment  to  be  inflicted  in  a  Christian 
State  ?  Objections  are  frequently  urged  against  it  on  the 
score  of  humanity ;  while,  on  the  other  side,  policy  and  care 
for  the  common  welfare  demand  it.  But  may  an  individual 
be  deliberately  sacrificed  for  the  common  welfare  ?  If  the 
right  to  inflict  capital  punishment  be  maintained  on  such 
grounds  as  these,  we  are  landed  in  the  theory  that  it  is 
merely  meant  to  deter  from  or  prevent  crime ;  and  this 
would  make  the  individual  a  means  or  sacrifice  for  the  general 
good.  But  man  must  not  be  treated  merely  like  a  noxious 
creature,  like  an  animal.  Society  recognises  him  as  a  rational 
human  being  not  only  by  rendering  him  harmless,  but  intnish- 
ing  him,  and  the  State  has  not  only  full  power  to  do  this,  but 
it  is  its  duty  to  do  it.  If  capital  punishment  is  to  be  justified 
on  ethical  principles,  the  grounds  assigned  for  it  must  be  in 
accordance  with  the  rights  of  the  criminal  himself,  as  well  as 
with  the  general  welfare  and  with  true  humanity.  And  this 
they  are  if  they  accord  M'ith  justice,  for  justice  contradicts 
no  other  virtue.  He  who  intentionally  murders  another  is 
unworthy  of  earthly  human  existence,  he  is  worthy  of  death. 
This  verdict  is  just,  it  may  and  ought  to  be  pronounced, 
unless  we  are  to  regard  the  lives  of  good  citizens  as  valueless, 
and  only  the  life  of  malefactors  as  inviolable.  On  moral  grounds, 
therefore,  it  is  not  permissible  to  declare  by  law,  that  no  crime 
is  henceforth  worthy  of  death.  The  humanity  of  such  legis- 
lation might  turn  out  to  be  very  inhuman  indeed,  inasmuch 
as  it  might  again  let  loose,  both  in  those  who  make  criminal 


CAPITAL  PUNISHMENT.  577 

assaults  and  in  those  who  defend  themselves  against  them,  a 
savage  element  which  is  held  in  check  by  the  public  admini- 
stration of  law.-^  Against  the  execution  of  capital  punishment 
it  is  especially  urged,  that  the  space  of  time  is  thereby 
shortened,  wliich  the  malefactor  has  for  conversion.  But 
conversion  is  in  God's  hands ;  Scripture  does  not  teach  that 
a  definite  locality  is  indispensable  to  it.^  It  is  opposed  to 
the  sense  of  Scripture  to  make  a  man's  final  destiny  depend 
upon  what  is  external,  or  upon  what  he  suffers.  On  the 
contrary,  it  depends  upon  his  personal  guilt.  Now,  with 
reference  to  the  latter,  experience  shows,  that  the  very 
seriousness  of  approaching  death  leads  many  criminals  to 
repentance,  that  the  solemnity  of  the  death-sentence  makes 
them  conscious  of  the  greatness  of  their  guilt,  whereas  lenity 
would  obscure  their  sense  of  its  enormity,  and  would  thus 
have  a  hurtful  effect.  Let,  therefore,  the  authorities  simply 
do  what  their  office  requires,  without  taking  those  factors 
into  account,  the  knowledge  of  which  is  denied  them. 
Experience  proves,  too,  that  it  is  just  converted  criminals 
who  acknowledge  that  their  crimes  are  worthy  of  death  by 
being  willing  to  suffer  it ;  and  even  if  such  expiation 
is  against  their  will,  they  at  least  wish  that  their  death 
should  have  a  good  effect,  and  should  strengthen  in  the 
community  at  large  the  sense  of  the  sacredness  of  human 
life.  Christian  humanity  shows  itself  not  in  abolishing  capital 
punishment  entirely,  but  in  limiting  it,  in  using  every  possible 
moans  for  the  conversion  of  the  transgressor,  as  well  as 
in  calling  to  mind  the  common  guilt  of  all,  whenever  an 
execution  actually  takes  place.  If  such  general  feeling 
became  strong,  capital  punishment  would  come  to  an  end 
in  the  right,  the  truly  humane  way — namely,  by  crimes  which 
are  worthy  of  death  no  longer  existing,^ 

Finally,  Christian  humanity  is  shown  in  the  right  of 
pardon.  Clemency,  especially  in  the  case  of  those  who 
exhibit  decided  signs  of  amendment,  must  not  be  prohibited 

^  The  New  Testament  is  in  agreement  with  these  positions  (Rom.  xiii.  4 ; 
Matt,  xx-vi.  52). 

-  [Cf.  System  of  Christian  Doctrine,  iv.   p.  412. — Ed.]     [Referring  to  the 
possibility  of  conversion  in  the  intermediate  state. — Te.] 

^  Trendelenburg  expresses   himself  to   the  same   effect,    XaturrecM,  %  70, 
p.  123  sq. 

2  0 


578  §  78.    CONTINUATION.       RELATION  OF  THE  STATE 

by  law,  any  more  than  capital  punishment  must  be  abolished 
by  law.  The  legal  abolition  of  capital  punishment,  even 
though  it  should  merely  take  the  shape  of  making  it  a  duty 
to  grant  a  reprieve  in  every  case,  would  effect  more  than  we 
may  desire  —  for  it  would  be  a  denial  that  the  crime  is 
worthy  of  death.  Sentence  of  condemnation  must  therefore, 
in  right  and  justice,  be  passed.  And  this  may  act  as  an 
incentive  to  repentance.  But  whether  the  sentence  should  be 
carried  out  or  a  reprieve  granted,  must  depend  upon  a  con- 
sideration of  the  particular  case,  and  upon  the  moral  state  of 
society.  The  criminal  must  have  the  fact  impressed  upon 
him,  that  he  has  forfeited  his  life,  and  has  no  right  to  pardon. 
But  if  pardon  does  not  create  the  impression  of  being  a 
privilege,  of  being  an  encouragement  to  crime,  it  may  and 
ought  to  have  a  place. 

§  78.   Continuation. 

Eelation  of  the  State  to  its  future  and  to  other  States.  An 
individual  State  must  not  seek  to  shut  itself  up  in 
itself,  in  its  present  existence,  as  if  it  were  an  absolute 
quantity,  and  needing  no  completion.  On  the  contrary, 
it  must  leave  room  within  itself  for  the  free  formation 
and  expression  of  public  opinion,  and  must  learn  to  lead 
a  social  life  with  other  individual  States.  Such  a  life 
demands  international  laws,  hut  excludes  the  'possihility  of 
a  universal  State. 

1.  The  organs  for  the  formation  of  public  opinion  are 
partly  free  associations  (§  70),  and  partly  the  press.  As 
long  as  these  do  not  become  extravagant,  and,  in  particular, 
do  not  interfere  or  claim  to  interfere  with  the  Executive,  but 
confine  themselves  to  the  ideal  region  of  the  interchange  and 
ventilation  of  thoughts,  liberty  must  be  granted  them,  unless 
they  should  corrupt  the  popular  mind  by  immorality  and 
irreligiousness.  For  the  State  must  recognise  morality  and 
piety  as  its  actual  foundation,  and  must  allow  no  injury  done 
to  them,  and  thereby  to  public  morals,  to  pass  unpunished. 
Energetic  repressive  measures,  however,  carried  through  in  the 
law  courts,  are  much  to  be  preferred  to  preventive  measures 


TO  ITS  FUTURE  AND  TO  OTHER  STATES.        579 

on  the  part  of  the  administration — hoth  in  themselves  and 
on  account  of  the  results  which  might  ensue.  For  in  the 
latter  case,  the  use  might  he  injured  in  preventing  the 
possible  abuse,  and  yet  the  use  is  essential  to  the  healthy 
existence  of  the  State.  For  when  there  is  no  public  spirit, 
the  State  is  without  a  soul ;  and  how  is  a  public  spirit  to  be 
formed  or  maintained,  if  there  is  to  be  no  public  opinion  ? 
However  much  it  may  be  the  duty  of  those  who  conduct 
political  affairs  to  hold  fast  to  the  institutions  which  have  been 
tried  and  tested,  it  nevertheless  becomes  every  Christian  states- 
man not  only  to  recognise  that  the  State  is  imperfect  in  every 
age,  but  also  to  take  pains  to  supply  its  deficiencies  and  raise 
it  to  a  higher  level.  And  for  this  end  it  is  necessary  that,  by 
means  of  debate  and  the  formation  of  public  opinion,  a  pre- 
paration should  go  on  in  the  sphere  of  thought,  for  the  intro- 
duction of  new  schemes  in  the  sphere  of  practice.  Without 
such  a  preparation,  the  best  measures  lack  that  intellectual 
support  which  they  require. 

2.  But  while  the  State  must  not  cut  itself  off  from  growth, 
from  its  future,  neither  must  it  shut  itself  out  from  other 
States.  No  State  has  the  right  or  the  need  to  be  the  sole 
ruling  one ;  but  all  are,  on  the  contrary,  independent  of  each 
other  and  co-ordinate.  On  the  other  side,  however,  it  is  one 
and  the  same  humanity  that  is  in  all  the  different  States ; 
there  is  not  a  different  class  of  human  beings  in  each  of 
them.  Christianity  has  quickened  this  consciousness  of  the 
unity  of  mankind  in  spite  of  its  being  split  up  into  nations. 
Hence  it  has  caused  an  increased  intercourse  between  different 
States.  The  effect  of  this  is  that,  on  the  one  hand,  more  strife 
arises,  than  if  all  nations  were  utterly  indifferent  towards  one 
another ;  while,  on  the  other,  the  Christian  era  shows  us  the 
beginnings  of  a  system  of  universal  international  laws  or 
rights  of  nations.  It  is  certainly  true  that  each  single  State 
requires  for  its  stability  a  national  basis, — a  fact  which  makes 
a  universal  State  an  impossible  ethical  idea  (§  75), — but 
nevertheless  each  State  must  be  open  to  active  moral  rela- 
tions with  other  States,  must  not  seek  to  injure  or  destroy 
them,  but  rather  to  defend  them  from  harm  ;  and  this  may 
be  done  even  in  honourable  warfare.  Christian  prudence 
cannot  come  into  collision  with  wisdom.     Those  bes'inninss 


580  §  78.    CONTINUATION. 

of  international  law  whicli  we  see,  make  it  possible  for 
Christian  nations  to  hope  that  one  day  Christian  princes  and 
Christian  peoples  will  unite  to  form  a  high  Areopagus,  to 
which  they  will  commit  the  task  of  settling  their  differences 
with  each  other,  so  that  Christian  blood  will  no  longer  have 
to  be  shed  by  Christian  men. 

3,  The  Christian  clmradcr  of  the  State  does  not  consist  in 
its  forbidding  non-Christians  to  be  citizens,  but  in  its  being 
what  it  ought  to  be,  viz,  just.  But  since  it  is  only  by  means 
of  the  Christian  principle  that  a  State  can  be  perfectly  just, 
this  fact  must  lead  to  beneficial  results  for  Christianity  in 
particular.  For  among  the  various  religions  it  is  the  Christian 
religion  alone  that,  by  its  history,  has  given  the  State  a  safe 
guarantee  that  it  will  exercise  a  blessed  influence  on  its 
citizens.  Hence,  just  from  its  own  special  standpoint,  the 
State  must  not  treat  other  religions  as  though  they  were  on 
the  same  level  with  the  Christian  religion,  so  far  as  their 
value  for  the  State  is  concerned.  The  State  is  just  when  it 
recognises,  that  Christianity  is  essentially  more  closely  allied 
with  its  own  principle,  and  gives  effect  to  this  recognition  by 
promoting  Christianity.  The  demand  for  abstract  religious 
freedom — the  demand,  that  is,  that  the  State  should  treat  all 
religious  parties  absolutely  aliice,  even  such  as  it  has  never 
tested — is  often  put  forward  in  the  name  of  justice.  But  it 
would,  on  the  contrary,  be  nothing  short  of  an  injustice  to 
treat  things  that  differ  in  the  same  way. 

War  is  not  in  itself  unchristian,  when  it  is  not,  as  regards 
its  purpose,  an  offensive  one.  The  State  has  to  guard  its 
lionour,  that  is,  its  sovereignty ;  and  when  this  is  assailed,  it 
is  its  duty  to  make  use  of  every  material  means,  and  therefore 
of  war  also,  to  repel  such  assault — an  imposing  example  of 
self-defence.  But  its  aim  is  not  to  destroy  the  enemy,  not  to 
strike  him  to  the  heart,  but  to  attain  to  an  honourable  peace. 


FUNCTION  OF  AKT.  581 


CPIArTEE  SECOND. 


AET. 

§  79. 

Art  presents  the  reality  of  the  Ideal,  of  Freedom,  of  the  Ee- 
conciliation  of  Mind  and  Nature,  under  a  scmUancc  of 
reality.  Its  principal  forms  are  the  plastic  and  the 
poetic  arts. 

The  Literatuke. — Winckelraann,  Lessing,  LaoJcoon.  Hegel's 
yEsthetik.  [Vischer,  Weisse,  Schleiermacher,  Fhilosophischc 
EtJiih  ;  Christliche  Sitte  ;  ^sthctih.  Schelling,  Fhilosojihic  dcr 
Kunst.  Herbart,  Encydopadic,  Sect.  i.  cap.  9.  Lotze, 
Gcscliichtc  der  jEsthetik  in  DeittscJdand ;  Griindzuge  dcr  jEs- 
tlid'ik.  Portig,  Kunst  mid  Rdigion.  Bethmann  -  Hollweg, 
Christentkum  iind  hildende  Kunst.  Dorner,  Kirdic  vnd  Rcidi 
Gottcs,  pp.  287  sq.,  Ill  srp  Liebetrut,  Voiii  Sdidncn  und  vora 
Sdiiiiucl: — Ed.] 

1.  The  Beautiful  is  the  Ideal  in  manifestation,  but  mani- 
festing itself  in  the  semblance  of  reality.  In  art-perception 
man  feels  the  ideal  as  actually  present ;  he  is  raised  above 
the  strife  of  opposites,  and  sees  them  reconciled.  But  art 
must  not  be  an  enervating  luxury ;  it  must  not  take  the  steel 
from  character ;  on  the  contrary,  the  ideal  world,  which  it  sets 
before  man,  must  give  him  a  more  ideal  conception  of  life,  and 
thereby  quicken  liis  sense  for  the  practical  and  his  energy. 
Art  has  a  right  even  to  have  special  moments  of  life  devoted 
to  it ;  but  this  does  not  mean  either  that  the  rest  of  life  is  to 
become  rude  or  ungraceful,  or  that  life  is  to  be  filled  up 
entirely  by  art,  but  that  art  must  be  like  Sunday  among  the 
days  of  the  week,  throwing  its  brightness  over  and  trans- 
figuring the  whole  moral  life  of  man. 

It  is  true  that  the  function  of  Art,  in  the  strict  sense  of 
the  word,  is  not  that  of  delivering  a  moral  lecture ;  but  at 
the  same  time  it  must  not  glorify  and  immortalize  existing 
evils,  nor  in  any  way  flatter  them  ;  on  the  contrary,  instead 
of  being  a  sensual  stimulus,  it  must  display  chastity  and 
purity  as  well  as  ideality,  and  thus  exert  a  purifying  and 
elevating  influence.     Art  is  not  covetous  of  aiiplause,  does  not 


582  §  79.    ART. 

desire  praise  and  honour  for  their  own  sakes ;  but  it  is  chaste 
and  true,  far  removed  above  fashion,  affectation,  or  mannerism. 
And  this  it  is,  when  the  artist  seeks  only  to  re^Dresent  some- 
thing which  has  already  made  a  powerful  impression  upon  his 
own  feelings,  seeks  to  make  it  touch  the  feelings  of  others, 
and  thus  to  propagate  the  emotion  it  first  awakened  within 
himself.  Art  has  the  power  to  elevate — if  but  for  the  time 
being — and  to  purify.  When  it  takes  a  national  form  and 
style,  it  is  an  important  means  of  refined  culture  to  a  com- 
munity. Even  artistic  production,  properl}^  so  called, — which, 
of  course,  is  only  to  be  found  in  artists  of  genius,  in  virtuosi, 
— has  a  wider  range  than  is  generally  supposed,  for  it  must 
have  a  place  in  refined  social  life.  This  is  true,  e.g.,  of  singing. 
But  in  addition  to  this,  it  is  desirable  that  there  should  be  a 
general  susceptibility  to  art ;  not,  indeed,  that  all  should  be 
art-connoisseurs,  and  still  less  that  all  should  practise  art- 
criticism,  which  is  of  doubtful  value  as  a  branch  of  art,  and 
was  hardly  mentioned  in  ancient  Greece  as  having  special 
functions  of  its  own.  The  forms  in  which  the  people  as  a 
whole  can  most  readily  take  a  share  in  art — both  in  the  way 
of  production  and  of  enjoyment — are  especially  jpodrij  and 
vocal  music;  it  is  of  especial  importance  that  the  young 
should  learn  classical  poetry,  hymns  and  national  ballads,  and 
the  practice  of  singing  them  is  of  special  value. 

But  the  Beautiful  has  a  much  more  general  significance 
than  we  have  yet  indicated,  since  it  forms  part  of  the  outward 
manifestation  of  the  virtuous  life  itself  The  beautiful  and 
the  moral  are  allied  to  each  other,  and  morality  is  not  mani- 
fested in  its  perfect  shape,  unless  an  artistic  sense  for  what  is 
noble  and  beautiful  pervades  the  whole  life  (§  62.  4,  61.  5). 
For  the  life  of  Christian  virtue  has  an  inward  melody  and 
measure,  a  certain  rhythm  and  harmony.  Christians  are  to 
be  living  a^aX^aQa  deov,  they  are  to  show  forth  the  divine 
So^a.  Here  the  artist  is  love,  which  does  not  merely  hold 
fast  to  morality  as  something  characterized  by  narrow  legal 
austerity,  but  which  exercises  a  free  sway  in  the  Christian 
life,  and  gives  to  all  manifestations  of  Christian  virtue,  both 
in  word  and  in  deed,  a  living  ideal  character. 

2.  Art,  properly  so  called,  falls  into  two  main  divisions  : 
literary  or  poetic,  and  plastic  arts.     In  the  latter,  it  is  iiaturc 


THE  PLASTIC  AND  POETIC  APtTS.  583 

that  furnishes  the  material  which  is  to  be  moulded  into 
beautiful  shape ;  there  is  here,  therefore,  somewhat  of  a  glori- 
fication of  nature.  In  the  literary  arts,  the  material — which 
in  this  case  consists  of  uwxls — is  itself  the  product  of  the 
mind,  and  nature  is,  as  it  were,  only  a  thin,  transparent 
vesture  for  the  ideality  of  the  thoughts  conveyed.  Here  the 
form,  which  in  the  former  instance  was  the  principal  matter, 
is  here  only  secondary. 

The  plastic  arts  present  the  beautiful  as  form  animated  by 
mind  ;  the  literary  present  the  beautiful  in  the  drapery  of 
words.  The  transition  from  the  one  to  the  other  is  found  in 
music  with  its  tone-waves  and  tone-imagery,  which,  however, 
address  only  the  most  intellectual  of  the  senses,  viz.  the  ear, 
and  hover  between  reality  and  ideality.  Each  of  these  main 
divisions,  again,  falls  into  three  subdivisions,  the  one  set 
corresponding  to  the  other. 

A.  Plastic  Arts.  Architecture  is  plastic  art  cliaracterized 
by  objectivity.  It  presents  ideals  in  their  abstract  universality 
and  simplicit}'' ;  and  for  this  reason  its  symbolical  power  is  all 
the  greater,  especially  in  the  representation  of  the  sublime. 
SculiJture  is  plastic  art  characterized  by  subjectivity,  and 
presents  what  is  concrete  and  personal.  Paintiwj,  finally,  is 
the  union  of  both.  For  it  groups  the  figures  of  sculpture  in 
accordance  with  the  principles  of  architecture  and  perspective. 

B.  Poetic  Arts.  These  occupy  a  more  purely  mental  region; 
their  oljjects  lie  in  the  world  of  mind;  and  although,  for 
example,  they  describe  nature,  yet  nature  must  first  be 
brought  to  ideal  or  spiritual  form  in  the  mind,  before  it  can 
be  presented  artistically.  In  the  Epic  we  have  poetic  art 
characterized  by  objectivity,  in  the  Lyric  by  subjectivity. 
The  Drama — like  painting — unites  both.  In  the  drama  the 
fabula  is  the  epic  root,  while  the  lyric  element  appears  in  the 
personal  dialogue  or  in  the  songs  (of  the  chorus,  for  instance). 
Tragedy  presents  the  beautiful  under  the  aspect  of  sublimity. 
Apparent  collisions  with  justice  occur,  but  the  result  is  a 
higher  Xemesis,  a  higher  revelation  of  justice.  Comedy 
represents  the  victory  of  truth  over  appearance.  A  play 
combines  both  the  tragic  and  the  comic  elements. 

All  the  different  arts,  music,  orchestration,  as  well  as  the 
three  kinds  of  poetic  art,  and  even  tlie  plastic   arts   (in  the 


584  §  79.    AET.       THE  DRAMA. 

shape  of  scenery  and  dramatic  representation),  appear  in  com- 
bination on  the  stage,  the  central  point  of  which  is  the  drama 
in  the  wider  sense  of  the  word.  There  they  mutually  support 
each  other,  and  succeed  most  completely  in  presenting  an 
ideal  picture  of  reality  in  a  beautiful  form. 

The  Theatre  must  not  be  regarded  as  in  itself  reprehensible. 
If  we  read  ancient  and  modern  classical  dramas,  and  even 
esteem  them  as  treasures,  there  is  no  reason  why  they  should 
not  also  be  recited  or  acted.  He  who  may  read  them  and  see 
in  his  mind  an  image  of  what  he  reads,  may  also  witness  their 
objective  representation  upon  the  stage.  This  holds  good  of 
the  public  in  general,  while  a  similar  observation  is  applicable 
to  actors  themselves.  A  player  must  not  indeed  lose  himself 
in  the  part  he  acts,  however  readily  this  may  happen  (§  68), 
or  identify  his  own  person  with  it.  For  then  he  becomes 
untrue ;  in  his  own  mind  he  must  always  remain  distinct 
from  the  part  he  plays,  and  only  live  in  it  and  represent  it 
by  his  imaginative  power.  If  he  is  carried  away  by  his 
feelings,  so  as  to  imagine  that  he  is  actually  the  hero  whose 
character  he  assumes,  then  he  is  no  longer  an  actor,  but 
begins  to  transgress  the  limits  of  objective  truth,  and  to  lose 
self-control.  From  what  has  been  said,  however,  we  see  that 
acting  is  morally  permissible. 

But  the  theatre,  as  it  exists  at  the  present  day,  exhibits 
many  deficiencies,  and  is  in  many  respects  morally  hurtful, — 
and  this  both  with  regard  to  the  pieces  that  are  played,  the 
vast  number  of  performances,  the  taste  of  the  theatre-going 
public,  and  the  spirit  that  prevails  among  actors  themselves. 
It  is  even  morally  objectionable  that  actors  should  form  a 
special  vocation  (§  68).  The  Greek  theatre  was  chaste,  and 
dramatic  exhibitions  were  infrequent,  being  held  annually  on 
the  occasion  of  great  national  festivals.  The  Greeks  employed 
no  unlawful  means  of  attraction ;  nor  was  there  any  need  of 
a  special  professional  class  in  connection  with  their  theatres 
— a  class  that  is  too  apt  to  degenerate  through  untruthful- 
ness, display  and  vanity. 

3.  Relation  of  Art  to  Religion  and  Christianity,  (a)  Art 
requires  religion.  It  must  indeed  have  no  laws  imposed 
upon  it  from  without ;  it  lives  and  works  in  the  atmosphere 
of  freedom,      Nevertheless,  if  there  is  a  want  of  true  inner 


EELATION  OF  ART  TO  RELIGION.  585 

life,  a  want  of  inward  harmony, — and  this  there  must  be  if  a 
moral  spirit  be  absent,  —  then  art  cannot  give  a  truthful 
representation  of  the  harmonious ;  in  other  words,  art  and  the 
beautiful  must  languish.  In  this  sense  it  must  be  said  that 
art  is  dependent  upon  morality  and  religion ;  and,  more 
especially,  that  there  is  an  inward  connection  between  Chris- 
tianity and  art,  or  that  it  is  only  through  Christianity  that 
art  can  arrive  at  true  maturity. 

(h)  Eeligion  requires  art.  Among  Christian  confessions, 
the  old  Eeformed  confession  shows  less  appreciation  of  art 
than  the  Lutheran ;  it  is  just  the  reverse  with  reference  to  the 
State.  For  the  Protestant  idea  of  the  State  has  been  carried 
out  most  completely  in  the  sphere  of  Eeformed  theology. 
Still,  even  the  Scotch  Eeformed  Churches  deny  that  they 
have  any  aversion  to  art  on  grounds  of  principle.  They 
simply  maintain  that  the  second  commandment  is  still  valid, 
and  hold  that  it  applies  not  only  to  representations  of  God 
Himself, — a  position  w^hich  might  easily  be  justified,  even 
from  artistic  considerations, — but  also  to  representations  of 
Christ,  especially  in  the  form  of  sculpture.  And  this  they 
do,  because  sculpture  has  more  of  the  appearance  of  reality 
about  it  than  painting,  and  therefore  tends,  in  this  case,  to 
engender  in  the  minds  of  the  uneducated  a  confusion  of  God 
with  the  creature. 

Earren,  prosaic  spiritualism  has  no  notion  of  the  fact  that 
the  body  is  a  gain  even  to  the  spirit.  In  art,  the  spiritual 
importance  of  the  body,  and  of  what  is  corporeal,  is  brought 
forth  in  its  essential  dignity,  and  made  an  object  of  perception. 
Art  is  a  kind  of  glorification  of  nature,  although  more  as  a 
prophecy  than  as  anything  else.  Eoman  Catholicism,  on  the 
other  hand,  places  art  too  high ;  it  mixes  testhetic  and 
religious  feelings. 

Primitive  Christianity,  on  the  contrary,  holds  a  middle 
course.  In  the  New  Testament,  instruction  is  conveyed  in 
the  language  of  poetry  and  parable,  while  singing  and  music  ^ 
are  both  recommended.  Further,  art  is  also  valuable  in 
public  worship,  and  even  in  the  formation  of  religious  ideas. 
For,  unless  the  imagiTiation  is  cultivated  and  developed 
(§  64.  1),  it  is  impossible  for  the  mind  to  form  a  vivid  image 
1  Cf.  Col.  iii.  16  ;  John  xv.  1  f.  ;  Matt.  vi.  28  f. 


586  §  79.    ART. 

of  Christ,  of  the  consummation  of  all  things,  of  the  majesty 
of  heaven,  or  of  the  angelic  world.  All  Christian  eschatology 
shows  that  Christianity  is  not  hostile  to  art,  but  that  it 
involves  the  final  perfection  or  glorification  of  nature.  And 
in  art  we  have  the  beginning  of  this  final  result.  In  these 
respects,  then,  it  forms  an  essential  factor  in  the  religious  life 
both  of  the  individual  and  of  the  community. 

But  art  must  likewise,  as  we  have  already  shown,  maintain 
its  independence  as  an  ultimate  end.  Although  it  must  always 
be  Christian,  that  does  not  mean  that  it  is  to  assume  a  specially 
Christian  form  and  manner,  nor  that  it  must  deal  only  with 
subjects  taken  from  sacred  history.  On  the  contrary,  its 
choice  of  material,  so  far  at  least  as  the  drama  is  concerned,  is 
limited  by  the  fact  that  nothing  which  pertains  to  the  essence 
of  religion, — Christ,  for  example, — no  religious  acts,  such  as 
prayer,  must  be  represented  on  the  stage.  To  do  so  would  be 
to  treat  religion  as  a  means,  and  would  therefore  be  profane. 
But  art  maintains  its  Christian  character  by  exhibiting  purity 
and  chastity  as  well  as  artistic  truth.  With  reference  to  the 
material  of  art,  the  only  limitation  laid  down  by  Schleiermacher 
is,  that  what  is  profane  or  worldly  must  only  be  employed  by 
art,  in  so  far  as  it  is  also  fitted  to  furnish  a  subject  for 
religious  art. 

4.  Relation  of  Art  to  the  Civil  Comtminity  and  the  State. 
The  importance  of  national  art  has  already  been  pointed  out. 
Art  in  this  form  exhibits  a  much  higher  style,  than  when  it 
depends  upon  private  patronage  merely,  and  serves  for  the 
adornment  of  private  houses,  etc. ;  for  in  the  latter  case  it  is 
always  apt  to  degenerate  into  triviality  and  impurity.  Hence 
the  State  must  take  an  interest  in  art.  It  cannot,  of  course, 
create  artistic  talent ;  but  it  can  arouse  it  when  it  exists,  and 
afford  it  the  possibility  of  free  development.  And  this  it  can 
do  by  providing  the  means  for  the  cultivation  and  mainten- 
ance of  art,  so  that  no  one  who  has  artistic  powers  may  lack 
the  opportunity  of  developing  them.  For  this  purpose  schools 
and  academies  of  art  must  be  formed,  and  in  connection  with 
these,  and  forming  as  it  were  their  libraries,  there  should 
be  art  collections  open  to  public  view. 


§  80.    SCIENCE.  587 

CHAPTER  THIED. 

SCIENCE. 

§   80. 

Science  too,  in  its  own  way,  has  claims  not  only  upon  all 
departments  of  human  life,  but  also  upon  all  men, 
although  in  different  degrees.  The  centre  of  the 
scientific  sphere  is  formed  by  the  learned,  properly 
so  called,  and  their  primary  functions  are  (cc)  research 
and  (h)  communication  of  scientific  knowledge  both  by 
word  and  by  writing.  The  way,  in  which  people  in 
general  take  a  share  in  science,  is  by  receiving  instruction 
and  by  reading.  ]\Ioreover,  since  science  is  necessary  to 
the  prosperity  of  all  the  other  spheres  of  life,  it  must 
also  be  furnished  with  the  institutions  which  are  essential 
to  its  self-maintenance  and  propagation,  as  well  as  to  its 
progress.  The  organizations  for  this  purpose  are  as 
follows  :  —  (1)  Schools  (Elementary  and  Middle-class 
schools,  high  schools  and  gymnasia).  (2)  Universities. 
(3)  Academies,  which,  in  addition  to  the  personal 
energies  of  their  members,  must  also  be  possessed  of  the 
material  means  for  carrying  on  their  work  (scientific 
collections,  libraries,  museums,  etc.).  Sound  science  has 
everywhere  a  national  character ;  nevertheless,  since  it 
is  truth,  and  truth  alone,  with  which  it  is  concerned,  it 
also  aims  at  a  general  interchange  and  arrangement  of 
scientific  knowledge,^  because  each  nation  is  specially 
fitted  for  the  cultivation  of  some  particular  side  of  the 
whole  organism  of  truth.^  It  is  the  duty  of  the  State  to 
ensure  to  science  the  possibility  of  its  vigorous  and  free 

^  The  law  of  hospitality  is  commonly  observed  among  academicians. 

-  In  particular,  the  English  and  French  on  the  one  hand,  and  the  Germans  on 
the  other,  mutually  supplement  one  another  ;  the  former  being  more  of  a 
practical,  and  the  latter  of  an  ideal  bent  of  miud. 


588  §  80.    SCIENCE. 

development ;  to  ensure  its  actual  development  is  beyond 
its  power.  And  that  the  progress  of  science  may  be 
rendered  possible,  it  is  necessary  not  only  that  those 
institutions  should  be  formed,  which  we  have  already 
mentioned,  but  also  that  there  should  be  liberty  in 
teaching,  and  also  liberty  in  the  publication  of  scientific 
works.  Christianity  has  nothing  to  fear  from  true 
science ;  secure  in  the  divine  certainty  of  its  own  truth, 
and  in  the  victorious  power  of  truth  in  general,  it  gives 
full  freedom  to  scientific  research. 

[The  LiTEiiATURE. — Cf.  especially  Schleiermacher,  Fhilo- 
sopliische  Ethik,  ed.  Schweizer.  Gclcgentlichc  GcdanJccn  uhcr  Uni- 
vcrsitatcn.  Wcrke,  3  Abth.  Bd.  i.  p.  537  f.  Hofniann,  Christl. 
Ethil;,  p.  317.  Zeller,  TJel)er  alcademischcs  Lehrai  und  Lerncn. 
Vortrdf/e  und  Ahhandlungcn,  iii.  Nr.  5.  Cless,  Die  Frarjc  nach 
dcmcthischcn  Werthe  der  Wissenscliaft,  1879. — Ed.] 

1.  All  the  great  advances  of  mankind  are  advances  in 
knowledge,  and  hence  in  science,  although  it  is  true  that  only 
intellectualism  can  hold,  that  the  culture  of  intelligence  is 
either  a  substitute  or  a  guarantee  for  religion  and  morality. 
All  the  best  discoveries  are  due  to  science.  It  is  true  that 
the  spheres  of  life  covered  by  religion  and  positive  morality 
are  in  no  sense  scientific  discoveries ;  they  precede  science, 
furnish  it  with  material  and  so  render  it  fruitful.  And  this 
holds  good  with  regard  to  Christianity.  But  science,  which 
then  appreciatively  directs  its  attention  to  the  higher  life  that 
has  been  won,  raises  the  appropriation  of  the  objective  contents 
of  that  life  to  a  higher  level,  and  to  a  firmer  and  more  secure 
objective  form.  And  these  contents  Christianity  itself  seeks 
to  become  through  the  organ  of  the  scientific  function.  To  be 
afraid  of  knowledge,  to  draw  up  Indices  librorum  irrohibitorura, 
is  unworthy  of  Christianity ;  a  Church  which  does  so  shows 
but  little  confidence  in  truth.  As  long  as  Christianity  con- 
tinued to  maintain  its  early  promise  and  vigour,  and  the  noble 
purity  of  its  life,  no  such  Indices  existed, — although  Tertullian, 
for  example,  has  as  many  heterodoxies  as  Origen.  The  case 
is  quite  different,  of  course,  with  regard  to  the  care  that  should 
be  exercised  in  maidng  a  wise  and  prudent  selection  of  books 


GEAMMAK  SCHOOLS.       UNIVERSITIES.  589 

for  the  various  stages  of  life  and  education ;  this,  however,  is 
a  matter  for  individual  judgment  (John  xvi.  12).  Science,  of 
course,  may  go  astray  and  so  do  harm.  But  if  it  could  not  do 
this,  neither  could  it  be  of  any  real  service ;  it  would  not  be 
free,  and  would  consequently  be  unable  to  be  truly  productive, 
while  it  would  fail  to  make  a  deep  impression  or  awaken  any 
confidence,  since  it  would  merely  work,  as  it  were,  to  order. 
False  science  is  not  to  be  refuted  by  force,  but  by  a  higher 
degree  of  scientific  knowledge,  which  exposes  the  contradic- 
tions in  which  false  science  is  involved,  and  proves  it  to  be 
science  in  appearance  merely.  And  this  inward  method,  slow 
and  tedious  though  it  may  be,  is  always  sure  to  succeed ; 
moreover,  it  is  a  method  which  must  always  be  possible, 
since  whatever  is  false  can  exist  only  upon  what  is  true,  and 
consequently  carries  its  enemy  in  its  own  breast. 

2.  In  connection  with  grammar  schools^  (gymnasia)  has 
arisen  the  opposition  between  humanism  and  realism.  The 
former  is  in  favour  of  classical,  the  latter  of  modern  culture. 
The  reason  why  they  cannot  come  to  an  agreement  is,  that 
both  of  them  have  in  many  ways  become  estranged  from  the 
Christian  principle.  As  a  natural  consequence  of  this,  an 
opposition  has  arisen  between  the  different  forms  which  the 
spirit  of  nationality  assumes  among  different  peoples — an 
opposition  which  Christianity  has,  in  principle,  overcome 
(Gal.  iii.  28).  If  modern  German  culture  is  dominated  by  a 
truly  Christian  spirit,  it  will  not  take  up  an  exclusive  attitude 
towards  classical  culture ;  and  conversely,  the  latter,  if  it  be 
(f)iXo\o<yla  in  the  true  sense,  will  also  respect  that  national  form 
of  culture  with  which  it  is  in  contact — nay  more,  it  will 
become  love  to  the  X&70?  who  became  flesh.  For  (piXoXoyia  is 
not  jnerely  love  of  words  or  language,  nor  even  of  artistic 
language  merely,  it  is  also  love  to  reason  and  to  the  world  of 
thought.  And  the  richest  world  of  thought  is  found  in 
Christianity,  in  which  the  innermost  thoughts  of  God  are 
revealed.  Christian  science  is  a  form  of  the  subjugation 
of  the  world  by  Christianity,  and  a  means  by  which  it  is 
carried  out. 

3.  Universities,  in  the  strict  sense  of  the  word,  are  to  be 
found  only   in  Germany,    although  even   here   they  fall  far 

^  Cf.  Marteusen,  I.e.  iii. 


590  §  80.    SCIENCE. 

short  of  their  idea.  In  Scotland  and  America  we  see  an 
effort  made  to  realize  true  university  culture.  In  order  that 
a  university  may  truly  discharge  its  functions,  it  is  necessary 
that  the  universum  of  knowledge  should  be  kept  in  view ; 
and  for  this  end  there  must  be  a  mutual  active  intercourse 
between  the  various  departments  of  knowledge,  while  each 
must  be  surveyed  in  its  connection  with  the  whole.  The 
faculty  of  philosophy  must  form  the  universal  medium  of 
intercourse  and  agreement;  when  this  is  not  the  case,  there 
cannot  be  any  possibility  of  an  active  interchange  between 
the  separate  faculties.  At  the  university,  students  must  seek 
to  know  the  Iruth,  to  apprehend  it  in  its  principles,  and  to 
love  it  unselfishly  ;  they  must  not  merely  seek  to  become 
fitted  for  some  definite,  practical  vocation,  or  to  be  made 
capable  of  performing  its  duties.  And  this  love  to  science 
must  dominate  all  their  studies,  so  that  the  latter  may  not 
degenerate  into  a  mere  training  for  earning  a  livelihood. 
When  they  do  not  rest  satisfied  with  a  knowledge  that  is 
superficial,  or  only  empirically  acquired,  when,  on  the  contrary, 
their  studies  lead  them  to  the  knowledge  of  truth  itself  in 
its  essential  principles,  so  that  they  master  the  truth,  or  rather 
so  that  the  truth  masters  them, — then  it  will  be  found  that 
the  truth  thus  gained  will  not  be  without  an  impulse 
towards  practice.  For  it  is  a  property  of  all  that  is  ideal,  to 
desire  to  exist  for  other  minds  also ;  this,  which  is  the 
universal  characteristic  of  truth,  may  be  called,  as  it  were, 
its  innate  quality  of  love.  And  every  one  who  has  been  taken 
possession  of  by  the  truth,  or  is  enthusiastic  for  it,  is  thus 
compelled  by  its  power  to  become,  in  his  own  sphere,  and 
alike  in  thought,  in  word  and  in  deed,  a  witness  to  the  truth, 
to  its  majesty,  and  to  the  blessings  which  it  brings.  His 
outward  practical  life,  in  his  vocation,  will  thus  become  the 
rich  fruit  of  his  inward  development  and  convictions.  And 
so,  without  any  declension  from  science, — which  is  a  sort  of 
intellectual  self-mutilation, — without  any  fatal  inward  rup- 
ture, the  transition  will  be  effected  to  practical  life  and  the 
duties  of  one's  vocation.  Superficial  study,  on  the  other 
hand,  without  a  real  love  for  truth,  either  lands  us  in  nega- 
tion and  confusion,  or  causes  us  to  take  a  leap  into  prac- 
tical  life^  and    to   make   a   violent,   immoral   hreach  between 


§  81.    IDEA  OF  THE  CHURCH.  591 

faith  and  knowledge.  But  a  faith  attained  in  this  arbitrary 
way  bears  its  character  stamped  upon  itself.  For  it  uncon- 
sciously transforms  evangelical  faith,  which  is  a  principle  of 
life,  into  a  work  and  law,  after  the  fashion  of  mere  intellec- 
tual and  lifeless  orthodoxy.  Where,  on  the  contrary,  moral 
stedfastness  and  freedom  in  the  investigation  of  truth  are 
preserved,  they  do  not  fail  to  meet  their  reward  in  the  joyful 
consciousness  of  the  great  harmony  that  subsists  between  all 
the  different  sides  or  regions  of  truth.  The  most  important 
thing  is  to  know  the  connection  of  all  the  various  spheres  of 
life  with  each  other,  the  connection  of  even  the  natural  or 
physical  with  the  moral,  and  of  the  moral  with  the  religious  ; 
for  such  knowledge  gives  a  direct  impulse  to  the  moral  and 
relisious  life. 


THIRD    SECTION. 

THE  ABSOLUTE  SPHEKE.       THE  KELIGIOUS  COMMUNITY. 

I.  Idea  of  the  Church, 

§  81. 

[Cf.  Glaubenslehre,  ii.  2,  pp.  689  f.,  782  f.,  784  f.,  804  f., 
844  f.,  876  f.,  883  f.,  887  f.,  899  f.,  910  f.,  924  f.,  977  f. 
—Ed. 

The  Church  is  the  community  to  which  the  absolute  religion 
gives  rise.  It  is  built  up  out  of  believing  humanity, 
through  the  power  of  the  Holy  Spirit,  and  on  the  basis 
of  the  Word  and  Sacraments,  and  is  a  constantly  self- 
reproducing  association  (§§  31,  34«,  71).  It  is  the 
moral  duty  of  all  men  to  belong  to  this  community.  As 
it  is  a  universal  human  duty  to  become  a  Christian, — for 
Christ  is  the  law  of  faith  (§§  40,  44), — so,  by  reason  of 
the  relation  subsisting  between  man's  consciousness  of 
himself  as  a  believer  and  his  sense  of  affinity  with  all 
men,  it  is  necessary  that  there  should  be  a  Christian 
religious   community  or  Church,  and  that  every  Chris- 


592  §  81.    IDEA  OF  THE  CHURCH, 

tian  should  attach  himself  to  it  as  a  living  member 
(§§  17.  3,  81,  71).  The  virtue  corresponding  to  this 
sphere  is  the  cliurchly  sense,  which,  while  remaining 
loyal  to  its  own  native  Church,  has  a  wide  heart  for  the 
one  ecumenic  Christendom,  and  is  equally  far  removed 
from  a  spirit  of  sectarianism  and  a  spirit  of  laxity. 
The  starting  -  point  and  the  goal  being  here  both 
universal,  the  way  to  the  latter  lies  through  the  his- 
torical forms  of  Church  life. 

Cf.  Schleierraacher,  Christlichc  Sitte. 

[The  Literature. — Petersen,  Die  Idee  der  christUchcn  Kirchc. 
Harless,  Kirchc  tmd  Amt,  1851.  Ilarnack,  Die  Kirclie,  ihr  Amt, 
ih'r  Ilcgiment,  18G2.  Kostlin,  Das  Wcsen  der  Kirchc,  hcleuchtet 
nach  Lchrc  und  Geschichte  des  iV".  T.,  1854.  Der  Glaube, 
393  f.  Walther,  Die  Stimme  nnsercr  Kirchc  in  der  Fragc  von 
Kirchc  v.nd  Amt,  1852.  Kliefoth,  Acht  BdcJier  von  der  Kirchc. 
Delitzsch,  Vier  Bilcher  von  der  Kir c he.  Lohe,  Drei  Bvxher  von 
der  Kirchc,  1845.  Kirche  itnd  Amt,  1855.  Eitschl,  Ucher  die 
Bcgriffe,  sichthare  und  unsichthare  Kirchc.  Studicn  und  Kritiken, 
1859,  2.  Begrundung  des  Kirchenrcchts  im  cvangelischcn  Begriff 
der  Kirchc,  1869.  Bechtfertigung  und  Versohnung,  iii.  J. 
JMlillev,  Die  unsichthare  Kirchc  dogmatische  Ahhandlungcn,  pp. 
278-403.  Andersen,  Das  j^'^'otestantisehe  Dogma  von  der  sicht- 
haren  und  unsichthccren  Kirche.  Theologischc  Mitarheitcn,  1841. 
Muenchmeyer,  Das  Dogma  von  der  sichtbarcn  und,  unsichtharcn 
Kirchc.  Witz^ch.,  Fraldischc  Theologie,  \ol.  i.  Kiauss,  Das  jrrotes- 
tantisehc  Dogma  von  der  unsichtharcn  Kirche.  Kierckegaard, 
Cliristcnthum  und  Kirche,  18G1.  Thiersch,  Vorlesungen  uher 
Protest antismus  und  Kcdholicismus,  1818.  Hofmanu,  Ethik,  p. 
164  f.  Martensen,  Christian  Ethics,  iii.  306  f.  Frank,  System 
der  christlichen  Gavissheit,  ii.  §  39.  Der  christlichen  Wahrheit,  ii. 
Schweizer,  Die  christl.  Glaitbcnslchrc,  ii.  p.  314  f.  A.  Dorner, 
Kirche  und  Reich  Gottes.  Schmidt,  Die  Lchrc  von  der  Kirche, 
1884.  Seeberg,  Der  Begriff  der  christl.  Kirchc,  1885,  Part  I. 
Lotze,  Milcroliosmus,  iii.  379  ;  Religionsphilosophic,  §§  94,  101. 
0.  Ptleiderer,  Rcligionsphiloso'j)hie,  2nd  ed.  ii.  c.  Grundriss  der 
christl.  Glauhens-  und  Sittcnlclirc.  Lasson,  Uehcr  Gegenstand 
und  Behandlungsart  der  Beligions'philosophie.  Harless  and 
Harnack,  Die  Kirchlichreligiosc  Bcdcuiung  der  rcincn  Lchre  von 
der  Gnadcnmitteln.  Cf.  the  literature  mentioned  above,  §  75. — 
Ed.] 

Note. — The  word  "  Church  "  comes  from  Kvptog  ;  the  bride 
takes  the  name  of  the  bridegroom.      The  controversy  as  to 


NATURE  OF  THE  CHURCH.  593 

whether  the  Church  should  be  set  in  a  superior  position  to  the 
other  moral  spheres,  is  an  idle  and  unfruitful  one  so  far  as  the 
Church  herself  is  concerned,  for  she  seeks  to  become  great  by 
serving.  That  which  is  befitting  to  religion  must  not,  without 
modification,  be  transferred  to  the  Church  or  religious  com- 
munity. On  the  other  hand,  the  Church,  regarded  in  her  real 
nature,  is  certainly  the  absolute  sphere,  since  she  has  directly 
to  do  with  God.  In  the  midst  of  the  other  moral  spheres,  she 
forms  the  central  sphere  in  the  Ivingdom  of  God  ;  she  is  the 
hearth  on  which  the  sacred  flame  of  the  higher  life  of  humanity 
is  fed.  She  has  to  do  with  the  sun  itself,  not  merely  with  some 
of  its  individual  rays. 

1.  As  to  the  essential  nature  of  the  Church,  the  Eoman 
Catholic  and  Evangelical  Churches  more  especially  are  at 
strife.  For  the  former  lays  stress  upon  the  external  side  of 
the  Church,  upon  the  Church  as  an  institution ;  nay,  it 
regards  the  outward  form  and  constitution  of  the  Church  as 
established  by  a  Divine  act.  Hence,  its  conception  of  the 
Church  is  altogether  a  dogmatic  one,  just  as  we  saw  with  regard 
to  its  conception  of  marriage  (not  with  regard  to  the  State, 
however,  for  it  insists  on  being  itself  the  true  State  ;  it  degrades 
the  State,  and  is  its  rival).  The  Evangelical  Church,  on  the 
other  hand,  takes  the  right  view,  however  often  it  may  be 
reproached  with  conceiving  of  the  Church  as  a  civitas  Pla- 
tonica.  It  is  true  that  it  also  ascribes  the  origin  of  the 
Church  to  a  Divine,  aet,  to  the  person  and  work  of  Christ, 
which  continue  to  operate  in  the  word  ami  sacraments}  But 
it  is  not  the  Church  as  an  institution  which  is  thus  directly 
produced;  it  is  believers,  the  redeemed,  who  are  first  of  all 
gained.^  It  is  only  when  a  foundation  has  been  laid  in  fait] c 
(§43  sq.)  that  a  fellowship  of  love  arises, — freely,  yet  by  an 
ethical  necessity.  The  Church  consists  of  vcre  credcntes ;  it 
is  a  congregatio  sanctorum,  that  grows  up  around  the  word 
and  sacraments.'^  Thus  it  is  an  ethical  product,  resting  upon 
the  act  of  God,  through  which  faith  comes  into  existence  ;  in 
other  words,  it  is  the  community  formed  by  believers,  who, 
even  when  they  do  not  know  one  another,  are  yet  ideally 
united  by  their  intercession  for  each  other  and  by  Christian 

1  Cf.  Syfitem  of  Christian  Doctrine,  iv.  §§  128,  134. 

2  Gal.  iii.  28,  ii.  20. 

^  Conf.  Aiifj.  vii.,  viii.,  not  a  poUtia  externorum  rituum,     Heb.  x.  24,  25. 

2  P 


594  §  81.    IDEA  OF  THE  CHURCH, 

love,  and  who,  wherever  they  meet,  quickly  imderstand  each 
other  by  reason  of  the  spiritual  kinship  of  their  higher 
nature. 

But  the  love  of  believers  does  not  remain  a  merely  ideal 
thing ;  it  seeks,  as  far  as  possible,  to  exhibit  itself  in  active 
exercise.  Believers  seek  to  realize  and  enjoy  their  union 
with  one  another ;  and  this  takes  place  through  their  self- 
manifesting  activity.  The  common  self  -  manifestation  of 
believers  is  displayed,  in  the  first  place,  in  the  sphere  of 
the  religious  life  ;  and  accordingly,  their  fellowship  with  each 
other,  which  already  exists  inwardly,  finds  outivarcl  expression 
in  their  associating  together  for  public  vjorship,  an  association 
which  is  the  soul  and  centre  of  Church  fellovjship.  Moreover, 
the  fellowship  which  believers  have  with  Christ  in  faith  and 
love  gives  rise  to  love  among  themselves  (§§  69.  1,  31.  3, 
45.  4),  and  this  love  again,  in  which  believers  stand  to  each 
otlier  in  a  relation  of  co-ordination,  gives  rise  to  active 
brotherly  love,  or  to  the  Church  as  the  manifestation  of 
fellowship  in  the  absolute  religion.  This  is  the  ahsolute 
dcriva.tion  of  the  Church;  it  is  peculiar  to  the  Evangelical 
Church. 

Still,  it  is  only  the  idea  of  the  Church  that  we  thus  obtain, 
not  its  empirical  form,  which  contains  non-believers  as  well 
as  believers.  In  order  to  arrive  at  the  latter,  a  second  factor 
must  be  introduced.  Love  also  is  present  in  faith  in  unequal 
proportions,  though  its  aim  is  the  removal  of  inequality.  The 
ecclesia  vere  credentium  does  not  manifest  its  activity  for  the 
sake  of  true  believers  alone ;  it  has  also  fcedagogic  functions 
to  discharge,  it  is  always  extending  itself  farther  and  farther, 
and  reacts  against  the  disturbances  which  it  suffers  from  the 
world  (§  69.  4).  In  addressing  itself  to  this  task,  it  does 
not,  in  a  Donatistic  spirit,  attempt  to  discard  the  unregenerate, 
but  rather  w^orks  patiently  with  them  ;  while  it  also  holds 
fast  to  its  Christian  contents  (word  and  sacrament)  in  their 
essential  principles,  carries  them  into  effect,  and  demands 
from  all  its  members  the  recognition  of  the  foundations  of  the 
Christian  faith.  In  this  way  it  becomes  the  ecclesia  large 
dicta^  and,  ever  carrying  on  a  process  of  self-purification, 
lives  and  works  as  the  salt  and  liglit  of  the  world.  Thus  it 
>  Apol.  ed.  Muller,  pp.  153-163. 


PUBLIC  WOESHIP.  595 

is  evident,  that  (and  why)  the  Church  must  at  every  time  not 
only  exhibit  the  character  of  a  Church  that  is  learning,  and 
therefore  needing  growth,  but  must  also  exhibit  self-manifest- 
ing  activity.  In  hoth  of  these  forms  of  Church  life  the  central 
element  is  felloiosliip  in  jniblic  ivorsJiip.  Fov  even  piety  grows 
by  exercise,  and  the  manifestation  of  piety  on  the  part  of 
mature  Christians  has  a  predagogic,  stimulating  and  edifying 
effect. 

2.  FellowsJdp  in  jJuMic  worship,  which  is  the  innermost 
sanctuary  of  the  Church,  and  exercises  a  ruling  influence 
over  everything  else,  deepens  and  intensifies  individual  piety 
(§50  sq.).  In  the  united  prayer  of  an  assembled  body  of 
believers  there  is  more  than  a  mere  act  of  man ;  for  iu  true 
public  worship  God  Himself,  in  the-  strictest  sense  of  the  word, 
is  present  in  the  midst  of  the  worshippers,-^  and  hence  God  and 
the  congregation  enter  into  the  closest  union  with  each  other. 
Thus  it  necessarily  follows  that  iu  public  worship  we  reach 
the  highest  moments  of  life.  Uniting  ourselves  to  God, 
we  unite  ourselves  to  the  personal  centre  of  the  universe, 
not  merely  to  reflections  of  Him  or  single  aspects  of  His 
nature  (such  as  the  State,  science,  etc.),  but  to  God  Himself 
in  His  majesty  and  love,  which  are  alike  unfathomable. 
Public  worship  therefore  is  not  merely  one  among  the  various 
legitimate  departments  of  life,  and  like  them  its  own  ultimate 
end  ;  it  is  an  absolute  end  both  for  God  and  man.  For  man, 
in  the  entirety  of  his  nature,  finds  rest  and  blessedness,  not 
in  any  single  region  of  life,  but  only  in  the  absolute  whole, 
which  is  God :  and  God  Himself  is  not  satisfied  until  this 
act  of  love  has  taken  place,  in  which  He  enters  into  the  most 
intimate  union  with  human  spirits.  Now  it  is,  of  course,  true 
that  congregations  upon  earth  are  always  limited  by  space 
and  time.  Nevertheless,  the  common  worship,  in  which  the 
believer  engages  with  those  who  are  more  nearly  allied  to 
him,  forms  the  natural  bridge  by  which  his  religious  life 
passes  out  of  the  isolation  of  mere  religious  feeling,  out  of  the 
idealism  of  the  merely  invisible  Church  or  fellowship  of  all 
the  children  of  God,  and  enters  the  sphere  of  outward  reality, 
— thus  becoming  a  life  in  which  the  whole  man,  both  in  body 
and  in  soul,  rejoices  in  the    living  God.     Wherever  public 

1  Matt,  xviii.  20. 


596  §  81.    IDEA  OF  THE  CHURCH. 

worship  is  held,  however,  it  must  be  the  true  spirit  of  Chris- 
tendom (and  Christendom  is  the  true  humanity)  as  inspired 
by  the  Holy  Ghost  that  finds  outward  expression ;  the  spirit 
which  praises  God  not  merely  as  the  protector  of  these 
individual  worshippers,  but  as  the  Father  of  all  mankind 
whom  He  makes  His  children  in  Christ.  The  true  spirit  of 
common  prayer  represents  the  true  catholicity  of  the  Church 
of  Christ  on  earth,  by  enlargement  of  range  and  heart  in 
intercession  and  love.  And  no  less  does  true  worship 
strengthen  the  bond  which  unites  the  Church  invisible  with 
the  Church  visible.  For  on  earth  the  Church  can  never  be 
such  a  complete  whole  as  is  presented  in  the  case  of  other 
communities  (marriage,  the  family,  the  State),  because  those 
who  belong  to  it  are  not  merely  its  members  on  earth,  while 
the  latter  themselves  are  scattered  throughout  many  different 
lands.  True  worship  draws  the  forces  of  truth  and  holiness, 
of  victory  and  immortality,  down  from  the  invisible  into  the 
visible  sphere.  Thus  in  its  public  worship  each  separate 
Church  and  confession  renews  its  life  as  a  member  of  the 
body  of  Christ,  animated  by  the  spirit  which  pervades  the 
life  of  the  whole,  and  which  unites  the  Church  above  to  the 
Church  beneath.  And  thus,  too,  it  protects  itself  from  the 
guilt  of  shutting  itself  off  from  the  truth  which  other  Churches 
represent,  and  from  the  gifts  with  which  they  have  been 
endowed. 

3.  The  virtue  whicli  corresponds  to  this  sphere  is  the 
churclily  mind  (§  55),  i.e.  an  active  interest  in  the  welfare  of 
the  whole  community,  shown  by  an  advocacy  of  the  interests  ot 
the  Church  community  and  a  co-operation  in  promoting  its  wel- 
fare,— always  in  accordance  with  the  God-appointed  vocation 
and  the  station  which  it  assigns.  This  churclily  sense  of  the 
Christian  is  shown,  not  merely  in  performing  certain  acts 
connected  with  the  Church,  such  as  attending  public  worship 
or  partaking  of  the  Lord's  Supper,  but  also  in  his  readiness  to 
sacrifice  energy,  time  and  means  for  the  aims  of  the  Church, 
and  to  promote  the  same  in  his  daily  life.  The  Christian 
Church  should  so  live  in  the  heart  of  each  individual  Chris- 
tian, that  in  his  whole  life  he  proves  himself  to  be  a  loyal 
and  worthy  member  of  it ;  or  that  it,  as  it  were,  acts  through 
him.     But  love  to  God  in  Christ  always  remains  the  first  and 


DIFFERENT  CONFESSIONS.  597 

foremost  thing  for  the  Christian.  Hence  he  can  never  be 
satisfied  with  a  Church  adherence,  which  has  not  as  its 
basis  a  living  adherence  to  Christ.  Should  the  former  seek 
to  pass  for  the  latter,  the  Christian  will  regard  it  as  a  mere 
appearance,  without  any  real  substance.  Since  the  relation 
we  hold  to  Christ  is  the  basis  of  Christian  piety,  it  is  through 
Christ  that  we  first  become  united  to  the  Church,  which 
without  Him  would,  for  us,  have  lost  its  centre. 

But  now,  in  consequence  of  the  influence  of  sin,  the  07ic 
Christian  Church  is,  in  its  historical  life,  split  up  into  different 
Churches  or  confessions.  In  this  state  of  things,  what  is  the 
attitude  which  the  churchly  mind  of  the  Christian  assumes  ? 
He  does  not  take  up  an  attitude  of  indifference  towards  the 
excellences  of  the  creed  of  his  own  Church,  but  at  the  same 
time,  being  alive  to  the  spirit  of  catholicity,  he  does  not  fail 
to  acknowledge  the  common  inheritance  of  truth  which 
belongs  to  other  confessions  as  well  as  his  own ;  nay,  he 
is  ready  to  recognise  their  superior  excellences  where  they 
exist.  For  it  is  for  the  good  of  the  whole  crco/jLa,  that  these 
have  been  conferred  by  the  Ke<^a\i]  upon  one  of  its  members. 
Hence,  vjhcrever  we  see  anything  that  is  Christian  in  other 
Churches,  we  are  bound  to  love  it,  and  neither  to  deny  or 
disparage  it,  lest  we  grieve  the  Spirit  of  Christ,  or  wound,  as 
it  were.  His  body  by  word  or  deed.  According  to  John  xvii. 
and  Epli.  iv.  1  ff.,  two  Churches,  which  are  at  one  in  acknow- 
ledging the  fundamental  facts  and  truths  of  salvation,  are  in 
duty  bound  to  hold  fellowship  with  each  other ;  and  this  is 
the  case  with  regard  to  the  Lutheran  and  Eeformed  Cliurches, 
which  cannot  refuse,  on  grounds  of  principle,  to  hold  sacra- 
mental fellowship  with  one  another  without  falling  into 
en'or  and  sin.  Of  course.  Christian  fellowship  is  not  a 
renunciation  of  the  convictions  we  have  won,  nor  an  accept- 
ance of  what  is  erroneous — on  the  contrary,  we  manifest 
love  by  combating  error  in  a  loving  spirit — but  it  is  the 
m^eans  by  which  different  Churches  maintain  an  interchange 
of  the  special  advantages  which  they  severally  possess.  On 
the  other  hand,  it  is  not  requisite  to  the  imity  of  the  Church 
that  Church  organization  and  usages  should  be  everywhere 
the  same.^ 

^  Conf.  Aug.  vii.,  viii. 


598  §  82.    CAEDINAL  FUNCTIONS  OF  THE  CHURCH. 

II.  The  Caedinal  Functioxs  of  the  Chuech. 

§  82. 

The  cardinal  functions  of  the  Church  are  self-manifestation, 
self-propagation,  and  self-purification,  the  last  of  these 
being  the  means  by  which  Church  unity  is  promoted.'^ 
It  discharges  all  these  functions  both  in  its  teaching 
and  its  life,  by  means  of  its  official  organization  as  well 
as  in  other  and  voluntary  ways. 

1.  Self -manifestation.  Many  hold  that  such  a  thing  as 
religious  self-manifestation  is  out  of  question  in  our  religious 
communities.  It  is  said  that  they  are  in  a  state  of  nonage, 
are  unchristian,  are  subjects  for  missionary  exertion,  that  in 
their  case  self-manifestation  would  be  untrue.  But  we  reply, 
they  have  been  baptized,  and  therefore  lefore  they  take  up  a 
position  hostile  to  the  Church,  they  are  under  the  laio  of 
Christian  faith  and-  life.  Such  a  state  of  things  already  makes 
Christian  self-manifestation  possible,  nay,  particularly  salutary 
and  beneficial.  By  Christian  self-manifestation  we  mean,  not 
simply  the  manifestation  of  objective  Christian  truth,  of  the 
love  of  Christ  to  men,  but  also  of  a  religious  life.  Even 
the  Christian  piety  which  savours  of  legalism  is  a  stage 
gained ;  it  is  a  surrender  to  the  love  of  Christ,  to  the  word 
of  Christ,  to  hearing  it,  and  meditating  thereon.  There  is  a 
pious  confession  of  sin,  there  are  pious  desires  which  ought  to 
be  manifested.  There  is  in  it  a  drawing  by  the  Father  to  the 
Son.  Moreover,  the  i^aedagogy,  under  which  we  may  too 
rashly  comprise  everything,  is  impossible  unless  there  are 
leaders,  who  by  self-manifestation,  by  demonstration  of  the 
Spirit  and  power,  enkindle  the  hearts  of  others.  Wherever, 
then,  the  Holy  Spirit  has  already  been  carrying  on  His  work 
by  means  of  the  word  and  sacraments,  there  must  the  Chris- 
tian spirit  also  manifest  itself.  It  must,  above  all,  show  its 
love  to  Christ,  its  union  with  the  fundamental  institutions  of 

^  This  division  of  the  cardinal  functions  is  based  upon,  §  81.  1.  The  Church  is 
a  fellowship  of  love  in  the  relation  of  equality,— then  its  action  is  that  of  self- 
manifestation — and  in  the  relation  of  inequality, — then  its  action  is  that  of 
propagation  and  purification. 


SELF-PEOPAG  ATION.  599 

Christ,  we  mean  the  word  and  sacraments,  to  which  the 
Church  is  bound  by  the  inner  law  of  its  life,  a  bondage  which 
is  perfect  freedom. 

We  have  seen  (§  51)  that  contemplation  and  ^:)ra?/cr  are  the 
essential  acts  in  which  individual  piety  is  manifested.  They 
are  also  the  acts  of  Church  piety  in  congregational  worship, 
but  in  this  case  they  are  united  with  the  objective  factors  of 
the  word  of  God  and  the  sacraments.  The  word  of  God  is 
the  ideal  of  all  devotional  language  in  public  worship,  and 
promotes  contemplation,  wliile  the  sacraments  directly  promote 
the  life  of  the  religious  community,  ^&)?/.  St.  Peter  gives  the 
exhortation — if  any  man  speaketh,  let  him  speak  as  it  were 
oracles  of  God.  Tlie  word  of  God  produces  religious  conscious- 
ness, </)(«?.  A  sacrament  is  not  merely  a  word  of  Christ  but 
an  act,  in  which  He  enters  into  perfect  union  Avith  believers 
and  the  congregation ;  and  this  act  of  Christ  is  the  type  of  the 
way  in  which  we  unite  ourselves  witli  Him,  that  is  to  say,  it 
is  the  productive  ideal  of  congregational  prayer.  We  should 
so  pray  that  our  prayer  becomes  an  act,  in  which  the  soul  is 
joined  in  the  closest  union  with  God  in  Christ.  This  is  the 
will  of  our  Lord  who  instituted  the  sacraments.  Christ's 
self-sacrificing  devotion  to  us  should  draw  forth  the  sacrifice 
of  our  prayer,  nay,  of  our  very  souls. 

In  the  self-manifestation  of  the  Church  in  public  worship, 
the  ideal  side,  namely,  the  religious  consciousness  of  the  com- 
munity, represented  in  common  contemplation  based  upon  the 
objective  tvorcl  of  God,  is  united  with  the  real,  namely,  fellow- 
ship in  religious  life  which  is  realized  in  common  prayer,  based 
upon  the  objective  sacrament.  This  fellowship  is  the  union  of 
consciousness  and  life,  ^w?  and  ^(a-q. 

2.  8elf-proparjcdion.  (ci)  EMensive.  The  manifestation  of 
the  unity  of  the  Church  with  God  in  Christ  is  not,  in  the  first 
place,  for  any  external  object,  but  for  an  object  contained 
within  itself.  The  congregation  engages  in  contemplation  and 
prayer,  not  in  order  to  produce  an  effect  upon  outsiders,  or  to 
convert  them,  but  for  its  own  sake,  and  in  order  to  experience 
and  manifest  its  fellowship  with  God,  or  its  possession  of  the 
supreme  good.  But  this  does  not  prevent  such  self-manifesta- 
tion from  being  at  the  same  time,  though  unintentionally,  a 
power  which  propagates  and  purifies  Christian  piety.      Who- 


GOO  §  82.    CARDINAL  FUNCTIONS  OF  THE  CHURCH. 

ever  looks  upon  a  congregation  engaged  in  worship,  and  truly 
possessed  by  the  spirit  of  devotion  and  prayer  (such  as  we  see, 
for  instance,  among  ourselves  on  Good  Friday),  cannot  fail — 
even  should  he  be  a  non-Christian — to  carry  away  a  deep 
impression,  a  sense  of  the  blessedness  which  the  congregation 
enjoys,  of  a  real  power  of  God  present  in  these  services,  and 
thus  the  latter  will  involuntarily  exercise  a  propagating  effect. 
Nevertheless,  since  the  Church  on  earth  has  always  to  combine 
self-manifesting  with  pcedagogic  functions  (§  81),  it  must  not 
merely  produce  unintentional  effects  upon  unbelievers ;  or,  in 
other  words,  it  must  not  organize  itself  with  a  view  to  self- 
manifestation  alone.  AVherever  such  a  tendency  becomes 
predominant  in  the  ritual  of  public  worship,  the  manifestation 
of  blessedness,  which  the  Church  makes  in  thanksgiving  and 
praise,  becomes  an  anticipation  of  the  victory  of  untruth,  of 
mechanism.  Por  the  manifestation  of  religious  life  made 
in  public  worship  must  never  go  beyond  the  actual  stage 
which  the  worshippers  have  reached.  Otherwise,  we  have 
the  beginning  of  mere  display,  the  principle  of  the  onissa 
solitaria,  and  we  offend  against  the  principle  of  all  manifesta- 
tion, against  truth  (§§  55,  65,  66).  The  Christian  congregation 
will  not  merely  manifest  its  needs,  its  longing  for  the  Bride- 
groom and  the  blessedness  of  comnmnion,  but,  strengthened 
by  the  enjoyment  it  has  of  the  absolute  good,  it  will  traffic 
therewith  for  the  purpose  of  bringing  it  to  those  who  as  yet 
have  it  not,  and  will  expressly  act  with  such  a  purpose.  Such 
is  the  self-propagation  to  which  Christians  are  impelled  by  the 
universal  purpose  of  the  love  of  Christ,  by  the  love  of  the 
Church  for  itself  and  for  the  brethren.  For  the  Church 
knows,  that  even  its  moments  of  triumph  cannot  as  yet  be  free 
from  pain  and  grief,  that  it  cannot  regard  itself  as  complete 
while  still  devoid  of  the  members  which  ought  to  grow  on  it. 
It  is  by  its  self-propagating  function  that  the  Church  grows 
in  extension. 

(a)  This  is  effected  in  a  jpcedagogic  form  by  the  education 
and  instruction  of  those  who,  by  means  of  infant  baptism,  are 
living  in  appearance  in  Christian  grace.  The  new  generations 
which  successively  grow  up,  are  appropriated  by  means  of 
catechetical  and  educational  agencies.  The  case  of  their 
elders  is  met  by  continuous  efforts  for  their  further  develop- 


SELF-PUEIFICATION.  GOl 

ment  in  the  conscious  possession  of  a  personal  justification 
through  faith,  and  by  pastoral  care. 

(6)  On  the  other  hand,  there  is  the  missionary  activity  of 
the  Church.  By  its  missions  to  Jews  and  heathens  the 
Church  is  ever  enlarging  its  borders  and  lengthening  the 
cords  of  its  tent.  According  to  the  purpose  of  Christ's  love, 
mankind  and  Christendom  should  be  coextensive.^ 

No  one  ought  to  be  able  to  plead,  as  the  reason  of  his 
unbelief,  that  the  offer  of  salvation  was  never  made  to  him. 
It  is  an  essential  function  of  the  Church  to  take  heed  that 
such  guilt  cannot  be  imputed  to  her.  Nature  in  every 
instance  expends  her  heartiest  efforts,  her  best  powers,  upon 
growth,  upon  reproduction.  This  normal  Church  activity  is 
of  specially  animating  power  for  our  own  Church  as  well  as 
others,  in  virtue  of  the  self-sacrifice  it  calls  forth,  the  enlarge- 
ment of  view  and  affection  it  produces,  and  the  consolation  it 
affords  amidst  the  corruption  and  the  contests  in  our  native 
Church. 

(h)  But  self-propagation  must  take  place  intensively  as  well 
as  extensively.  Everything  that  really  lives  has  within  itself 
a  tendency  to  grow.  And  this  tendency  will  be  self-operative, 
when  that  which  checks  and  restrains  it  is  done  away  with. 
And  this  consideration  points  to  the  Church's  function  of 
self-purification. 

3.  Self  -  purification.  Growth  in  extent  will  have  an 
externalizing  effect,  unless  it  is  at  the  same  time  a  growth  in 
intensity.  It  becomes  intensive  in  the  Church  by  the  same 
process  as  in  individuals — by  purification  (§  48)  ;  the  shadows 
of  the  unconverted  world  reach  far  into  the  Church,  though 
not  to  its  centre,  which  always  remains  in  unvarying  bright- 
ness, in  the  light  of  eternity.  Hence  intensive  growth  is 
carried  on  by  two  processes.  There  is,  on  the  one  hand,  a 
continued  assimilation  of  those  vital  forces  wdiich  are  Divine, 
accompanied  by  the  use  of  such  pure  forces  as  already  exist, 
for  the  purpose  of  purification.  There  is,  on  the  other,  a 
continual  rejection  of  error,  the  intellectual,  and  sin  the  actual 
opposite  to  the  Church,  for  the  purpose  of  giving  free  action 
on  behalf  of  the  kingdom  of  Christ,  and  for  the  appropriation 
of  the    TTvev/xa,   to   those   powers   which   were   restrained  or 

^  Matt,  xxviii.  20,  xxiv.  14. 


6  02  §  82.    THE  CARDINAL  FUNCTIONS  OF  THE  CHURCH. 

corrupted  by  the  spirit  of  evil.  Hence  the  Church  can  only 
be  regarded  as  Christian,  if  engaged  in  a  course  of  continual 
reformation  and  renovation.  It  is  blameable  sloth  and  pre- 
sumption to  think,  that  a  single  century  could  complete  the 
work  of  reformation.  This  third  essential  function,  viz.  self- 
purification,  has  to  be  exercised  against  all  the  stains  and  im- 
perfections with  which,  through  sin  or  error,  the  Church  may 
as  a  whole,  or  in  its  individual  members,  whether  externally 
or  internally,  be  affected.     To  it  belongs, — 

(a)  The  action  of  the  whole  body  against  the  power  of  sin 
and  error  in  individuals  by  Church  discijjline.  This  is 
authorized  by  Matt,  xviii.  1 8  ;  1  Cor.  v. ;  2  Cor.  ii. ;  Tit.  iii. 
10.  It  has  been  disputed  whether  the  saving  of  the  sinner, 
the  amendment  of  him  who  has  caused  notorious  scandal,  or 
the  warning  which  would  preserve  from  infection,  or  the 
honour  of  the  Church,  should  be  the  governing  principle  of 
such  discipline.  No  safe  point  of  departure  for  Church  dis- 
cipline— that  nervus  ecclcsice,  according  to  Calvin — will  be 
found,  if  it  is  regarded  as  penal  power,  except  in  the  sense  of 
e\e<y)(eLv.  But  neither  is  the  first  view  sufficient.  For  the 
amendment  of  the  offender  is  not  in  the  power  of  man.  If 
only  such  amendment  could  make  Church  discipline  lawful,  it 
must  either  not  exist  at  all,  or  else  must  cease  just  where  it  is 
most  needful.  On  the  contrary,  the  certain  and  u/iassailahle 
2)oint  of  view  is  that  it  is  the  Church's  right  and  duty  to  assert 
itself  against  offences,  and  not  by  silence  to  draw  down  upon 
itself  the  saying :  qui  tacet,  consentirc  vidctur.  In  Church 
discipline  the  Church  is,  in  the  first  place,  engaged  in  vindi- 
cating its  own  honour;  for  if  that  is  injured,  her  mission  to  the 
world  is  made  void.  Against  notorious  sinners,  who  live  as  if 
a  life  of  impenitence  were  compatible  with  Christianity  and 
Church-membership,  the  Church  has  to  secure  her  own  dignity 
by  renouncing  all  connection  with  sin  and  all  toleration  of 
sin  in  herself.  By  this  means  oftence,  i.e.  the  infectious 
power  of  sin,  is  already  done  away  with.  Such  an  assertion 
of  dignity  on  the  part  of  the  Church  is  certainly  an  act  of 
justice — in  the  first  place  towards  herself;  she  must  not  be 
partaker  of  other  men's  sins,  but  must  separate  from  the 
unholy.  And  thus  also  will  she  most  surely  prepare  the  way 
for  the  restoration  of  those  who  turn  the  <n'ace  of  God  into 


CHURCH  DISCIPLINE.  603 

lascivioiisness.  "We  see,  then,  that  when  the  Church  is 
content  with  fulfilling  the  duty  of  preserving  her  own  purity, 
she  is  thereby  most  certainly  on  the  road  towards  meeting  the 
first  requirement,  viz.  the  awakening  and  amendment  of  the 
sinner.  For  only  by  walking  in  the  way  of  justice  and  law, 
and  not  by  overleaping  them,  can  that  of  restoration  and  grace 
be  found.^ 

Note. — Churcli  discipline  must  not  become  a  civil  penalty. 
The  stress  laid  upon  tlie  honour  of  the  Church  must  not  take 
place  in  tliat  external  and  secular  manner,  wliich  the  hier- 
archical spirit  would  desire.  Christian  maintenance  of  honour 
includes  both  wisdom  and  ministering  love  (§  65),  for  it  is  the 
Church's  honour  to  minister.  Self-maintenance  against  all  that 
is  unholy  is,  at  the  same  time,  love  to  the  world,  to  which  the 
Church  can  be  of  no  service  if  tlie  salt  has  lost  its  savour. 

(&)  But  corruption  in  doctrine  may  also  seize  upon  the 
empirical  Church  to  a  still  greater  extent,  in  heresy  and 
schism.  Even  those  who  act  in  the  name  of  the  Church 
may  themselves  be  overtaken  by  them,  as  in  the  time  of  the 
Reformation.  Then  there  is  nothing  left  but  the  contrary 
process  to  that  just  described,  viz.  the  action  of  the,  individual 
upon  the  Church  in  the  way  of  reform  and  purification ;  for 
then  the  Church  must  live  in  the  bosom  of  each  individual. 
If  corruption  maintains  itself  against  such  action,  it  may 
become  the  cause  of  a  division  in  the  Church.  The  reforming- 
process  must  nevertheless  continue,  however  powerful  the 
party  of  corruption  may  be.  The  reforming  force  must  ally 
itself  to  whatever  is  true  within  the  Church,  and  neither 
forsake  the  word  of  God  nor  the  Cliurch.  If  the  Eeformers 
should  then  be  excommunicated  by  the  religious  community, 
which  would  by  such  an  act  excommunicate  itself  from  the 
truth,  if  they  are  thus  passively  placed  in  a  state  of  separa- 
tion, even  then  the  purifying  energy  of  love  must  not  cease 
to  bear  its  testimony  to  the  truth.  In  this  way  the  process 
of  purification  will  at  last,  according  to  the  Lord's  promise, 
become  also  a  process  of  unification  (cf.  §  81.  3,  §  55). 

^  Compare  on  Church  discipline,  Glaithenslehrf,  ii.  2,  pp.  911,  883  sq.  (895, 
897,  906). 


CO 4  §  83.    CHUECH  ORGANIZATION. 

III.  Church  Organization. 
§  83. 

It  is  by  its  government  that  the  Church  is  organized  for  the 
performance  of  its  three  cardinal  functions  (§  82). 
Organization  being  a  means  and  not  an  end,  must  be 
sufficiently  elastic  to  correspond  to  the  varying  needs  of 
different  ages.  It  must  embrace  the  ideal  side,  viz.  that 
of  Christian  consciousness  or  doctrine,  and  the  actual  side, 
viz.  that  of  practice  in  its  self-manifesting,  its  self-pro- 
pagating, and  its  self-purifying  action.  The  functions  of 
teaching,  governing,  and  ministering  are  of  Divine  institu- 
tion, not  so  the  form  of  their  administration,  and  still  less 
the  individuals  who  perform  them.  The  Church,  with  its 
organized  offices,  must  also  leave  room  for  voluntary  exer- 
tions, and  Christian  associations  in  many  varying  forms. 

[The  Literature. — Comp.  Glanhcnslckrc,  ii.  2,  pp.  784  f.,  883  f. 
Schleiermacher's  Darstcllung  vom  Kirchcnrcgimcnt,  ed.  by  Weiss. 
Spener,  Vom  gcistlichcn  Fricstcrthum.  Hermann,  Ucbci^  die 
neucstc  Bestreitung  dcr  Autoritdt  des  kircJdichcn  Sgonhols.  Die 
nofhivcndigen  Grundlagcn  eincr  die  consistoricde  und  synodcde 
Ordmtng  vcrcinigenden  Kirchcnverfassung.  Lechler,  Die  7icu- 
testamentliche  Lchrc  vom  heiligen  Amt.  Hotiing,  Grundsdtze 
eixmgelischer  Kirchenverfassimg.  Steinmeyer,  Begriff  des  Kirchen- 
Tcgiments.  Zezschwitz,  Die  wescntlichcn  Verfassungszicle  der 
luthcrischen  Beformation.  System  dcr  Katcchetik,  vol.  i.  p.  687  f. 
Harnack,  Die  freie  hdlieri&clie  Vollxshirche.  Jakoby,  StacUskirche, 
Freikirehe,  Landeskirclie.  Jacobson,  Studien  und  Kritikcn,  1867, 
uher  den  Begriff  der  Vocation  und  Ordination.  Nitzsch,  Prak- 
tische  Thcologic,  ii.  452  f.  Richter,  Gesehiehte  der  cvangelischcn 
Kirchenvcrfassung.  Hundeshagen,  Bcitrdge  zur  Kirchcnverfas- 
sung sgcschichte.  Kliefoth,  Lit'iLrgisclie  Ahhandlungcn,  i.  p.  341  f. 
Kietschel,  Luther  und  die  Ordinatioji,  1883.  Comp.  the  litera- 
ture, §  81.] 

1.  The  ethic  necessity  of  organization.  If  the  Church  is  to 
be  an  actual  power,  effecting  an  actual  work  in  and  among 
human  beings,  and  not  a  civitas  Platonica,  it  must  have  an 
organization  based  upon  its  own  principle.  By  giving  to  her 
Church  activity  the  form  of  settled  official  functions  performed 


ITS  ETHIC  NECESSITY.  605 

in  the  name  of  the  whole  community,  both  the  existence  and 
principle  of  the  Church  are  rescued  from  arbitrariness  and 
chance,  and  a  connected,  stable,  and  orderly  instrumentality 
secured.  The  regulation  of  official  functions  is  efiected  by 
Church  government.  Office  implies  a  union  of  right  or  power 
and  duty  by  means  of  commission.  The  Church  is  called 
aTv\o<;  Kal  eSpatcofia^  and  this  she  actually  is  by  means  of 
her  offices,  although  the  roots  of  her  power  are  planted  in  the 
invisible  world.  The  varied  necessities  of  the  Church  are  met 
by  the  varied  gifts  of  the  Spirit;"  while,  on  the  other  hand,  the 
capacity  thus  bestowed  can  only  develop  its  full  benefits, 
when  the  special  vocation  in  which  it  can,  by  express  adapta- 
tion and  exercise,  attain  to  virtuous  aptitude,  is  determined 
by  some  stable  appointment.^ 

It  is  true,  indeed,  that  offices  in  the  Church  are  of  a  funda- 
mentally different  character  from  offices  in  the  State.  The 
contrast  of  rulers  and  subjects  is  softened  down  in  the  Church 
to  the  contrast  of  guides  and  guided,  of  givers  and  receivers. 
Church  officials  should  not  have  dominion  over  the  faith  of 
their  fellow-Christians,  but  be  helpers  of  their  joy.'*  Their 
part  is  to  minister,  they  are  therefore  authorized  to  give. 
But  hencjicicc  non  ohtrucluntur ;  they  must  bring  souls  to 
Christ,  and  must  themselves  decrease  that  He  may  increase ;  '^ 
i.e.  they  should  sccJc  to  reconcile  the  difference  between  giving 
and  receiving,  by  bringing  those  whom  they  teach  to  Christian 
maturity. 

It  is  further  the  duty  of  every  Christian  to  show  forth,  in 
his  tvalk  and  conversation,  the  praises  of  Him  who  hath  called 
him.  In  the  word  of  God  the  blessings  of  salvation  are 
entrusted  to  every  believer  as  such.  Christians  are  a  pro- 
phetic, priestly  and  royal  generation,  and  thus  are  in  the 
abstract  capable  of  dispensing  the  word  and  sacraments. 
The  use,  however,  of  this  capacity  is  quite  another  matter. 
There  must  be  a  public  use  of  it  in  the  name  of  the  whole 
body  of  Christians,  because  a  commission  was  given  to  the 
whole  body  to  dispense  the  word  and  sacraments  to  mankind. 

'  1  Tim.  iii.  15  ;  Matt.  xvi.  18.  -  1  Cor.  xii,  14-31,  xiv. 

^  1  Cor.  xiv.  26,  40. 

*  2  Cor.  i.  23  ;  1  Pet.  v.  1-6  ;  John  xiii.  12  sq. 

*  John  iii.  28-30. 


606  §  83.    CHURCH  ORGANIZATION. 

And  an  individual  cannot  give  himself  this  commission  to  act 
in  the  name  of  the  entire  body.  The  Church  has  likewise  its 
duty,  and  must  so  organize  itself  that  all  things  may  be  done 
in  order.  Only  the  Church  is  in  a  condition  to  secure,  by  its 
governmental  action,  that  basis  and  rule  of  fellowship,  a  stable 
and  well-ordered  administration  of  the  word  and  sacraments. 
It  is  her  duty  to  institute  offices  where  they  do  not  as  yet 
exist.  It  is  tliat  of  the  individual  to  enter  into  Church 
fellowship,  and  consequently  to  adhere  and  accommodate 
himself  to  the  instrumentality,  which  it  is  the  Church's  duty 
to  employ  in  the  fulfilment  of  her  mission. 

If  this  order  is  to  be  carried  out  successfully,  an  organic 
hody  must  exist  through  the  institution  of  settled  offices.  The 
individual  Christian  must  not  desire  to  assert  his  particular 
right.  That  which  is  to  be  done  in  the  name  of  the  whole, 
which  is  the  mission  of  the  whole,  must  not  be  arbitrarily 
undertaken  by  the  individual,  in  his  own  name  and  by  his 
own  authority.  It  is  precisely  from  the  essential  equality  of 
all,  through  the  priesthood  of  all  Christians,  that  Luther  infers 
that  not  every  one  may  presume  to  teach  publicly  and  to 
administer  the  sacraments,  except  in  cases  of  necessity  and 
isolation.  "  If  the  office  belongs  to  all,  why  dost  thou  arrogate 
it  to  thyself  singly  ?  "  Here,  as  elsewhere,  it  holds  good  that 
it  is  unethical  not  to  seek  the  ohjective  confirmation  for  the 
suljective  inwards  call  (§  68).  Strictly  speaking,  it  is  not  an 
office,  but  only  a  duty  that  devolves  upon  every  believer. 
An  office  is  a  vocation  conferred  by  the  joint  will  of  the 
entire  body  upon  an  individual,  to  act  constantly  and  con- 
sistently in  the  name  of  the  whole.  In  this  case  authority 
or  right  and  duty  are  identical. 

On  the  other  hand,  it  is  just  as  reprehensible  when  offices 
are  hierarchically  constituted,  or  when  it  is  sought  to  supple- 
ment them  by  sacramental  ordination ;  ^  the  office  is  bestowed 
upon  the  Church,  to  which  the  laity  belong  as  well  as  the 
priesthood.  It  is  indeed  the  Church's  duty  to  transfer  it  to 
individuals,  because  this  is  the  most  judicious  manner  of 
administering  its  functions.  But  this  transference  to  indi- 
viduals of  the  offices  given  to  the  Church  is  no  sacramental 

^  See,  on  the  other  hand,  Artie.  Smalc.  ed.  Miiller,  pp.  341,  342,  ordinatio 
=comprobatio  electionis. 


LIMITS  OF  OFFICIAL  ORGANIZATION.  607 

act  of  Christ,  but  an  ethical  act  of  the  community,  or  of  those 
authorized  to  act  for  it.  The  divine  calling  takes  effect  by 
means  of  the  human  freedom  of  the  community,  and  therefore 
in  an  ethical  manner.  The  assurance  of  a  man's  consciousness 
that  lie  has  a  call  from  God,  no  more  suffers  from  such  ethical 
intervention,  than,  e.g.,  a  husband's  consciousness  of  being  in  a 
state  ordained  of  God  suffers  from  the  intervention  of  free 
choice  on  the  part  of  both  husband  and  wife.  It  is  legalism 
to  see  the  Divine  only  where  God  acts  exclusively,  without 
the  Church  and  without  human  agency.  It  is  equally  so  to 
perceive  only  arbitrariness  where  human  freedom  co-operates. 
On  the  other  hand,  it  is  of  the  essence  of  Christian  organism 
for  the  Divine  and  the  human  to  be  combined  therein. 

2.  The  limits  of  official  oryanimtion.  It  is  certain  that 
every  official  act  cannot  be  organized.  Here,  too,  it  is  evident 
that  the  Church  cannot  present  so  rounded  off  an  appearance, 
as  other  moral  spheres.  The  Church  is  not  absorbed  in  the 
office.  It  has  other  functions  besides  those  performed  by 
appointed  office-bearers.  It  is  only  Koman  Catholicism  that 
insists  on  seeing  the  Church  only  in  the  clergy,  the  ecclesia 
repraesentiva.  The  voluntary  and  the  official  agency  of  the 
Church  must,  however,  be  distinguished.  The  former  has 
attained  special  importance  in  the  various  Christian  societies 
for  missionary  and  other  purposes.  It  is  a  short  -  sighted 
notion  that  regards  these  two  parts  of  one  whole  as  a 
hindrance  to  each  other.  The  regular  official,  who  acts  in  the 
name  of  the  Church,  has  set  before  him  this  test  of  his 
evangelical  tact  and  power:  Does  he  suffer  the  members  of 
the  Church  to  be  inactive  and  unemployed,  or  do  the  babes 
in  Christ  attain  maturity ;  is  he  the  means  of  so  kindling 
the  zeal  of  Christians,  that  they  cannot  help  becoming  his 
fellow-workmen  and  helpers  ?  For  Christians  will  not  desire 
to  act  on  their  own  responsibility,  or  to  make  fresh  starts  as 
tliough  no  Christian  work  had  been  in  operation  before  them, 
but  to  work  in  the  closest  possible  union  with  efforts  already 
existing.  Such  a  disposition  will  lead  them  to  regard  the 
official  as  the  centre,  by  which  alone  stability  and  order  can 
be  imparted  to  the  agency  of  the  laity.  Where  the  two 
elements  of  lawfully  established  office  and  voluntary  effort 
combine   in    Church    work,    we   have   a    realization    of   that 


608  §  83.    CHUKCH  ORGANIZATION. 

evangelical  Church  life,  which  will  make  fruitful  and  elevate 
all  who  take  part  in  it. 

Unfortunately,  among  ourselves  tlie  copious  variety  of 
offices  and  gifts,  spoken  of  in  the  ISTew  Testament,  have 
for  a  long  time  often  dwindled  into  one  office,  from  which 
everything  was  required  which  it  could  not  possibly  perform. 
To  this  state  of  things  many  of  the  clergy  have  accustomed 
themselves  as  though  it  were  an  ideal  condition,  and  when 
any  higher  ideal  is  placed  before  them  they  can  see  only 
anarchy  and  danger.  At  the  same  time,  they  regard  with 
hostility  any  State  or  ecclesiastical  authorities,  who  are  help-r 
ing  to  put  an  end  to  so  indefensible  a  system.  The  New 
Testament  says  nothing  of  devolving  all  the  functions  of  the 
Church  upon  one  office  or  one  person  in  a  congregation. 
Wherever  this  has  taken  place.  Church  life  has  been  paralysed, 
or  at  best  has  displayed  great  immaturity.  On  the  other 
hand,  where  there  has  been  a  multiplicity  of  offices,  as,  e.g.,  of 
old  in  the  Churches  of  Corinth  and  Ephesus,  there  many 
other  agencies  have  also  existed.  Nor  is  it  the  intention  of 
the  evangelical  confessions  either  to  make  the  "  preacher's  "  the 
sole  office,  or  to  suffer  all  voluntary  Church  work  to  be 
absorbed  by  officialism.  Even  teaching  is  not  entirely  taken 
from  the  laity,  nor  all  preaching  of  the  word,  all  fiaprvpeiv 
forbidden  them.  On  the  contrary,  Church  order  is  considered 
as  sufficiently  observed,  if  the  'piiblice  clocere  et  administixire 
sacramcnta  takes  place  only  in  the  name  of  the  Church,  and 
therefore  by  means  of  Church  officials.  This  leaves  room  for 
religious  meetings  for  the  purpose  of  edification,  for  societies, 
for  associations  for  Church  purposes.^  To  this  must  in  our 
days  be  added,  that  after  the  example  of  the  ancient  Church, 
laymen  may  also  take  part  officially  in  the  work  of  the 
diaeonate,  and  in  general  care  for  the  Church  life  of  the 
commnnity.  Not  till  this  is  permitted  will  the  gifts  latent 
in  it  become  active  and  fruitful. 

The  Christian,  as  before  observed,  is  to  manifest  in  all  his 
actions  the  churchly  mind,  nay,  the  Church  is  to  live  in  him  ; 
but  it  is  at  the  same  time  impossible  that  all  should  in 
every    respect    perform    the    functions    of    officials    of    the 

^  Art.   Smalc.   ed.    Mliller,    p.  320   iv,,   mutimm   collor[uium   et   consolatio 
fratrum. 


MODE  OF  CHURCH  OEGANIZATION.  609 

orcranized  Church.  Hence  it  necessarily  follows  that  we 
must  in  our  ethical  notion  of  the  Church  maintain  the  needful 
distinction  between  the  settled  and  organized  Church,  which 
is  to  be  the  central  point  for  the  world  of  Church  life,  and 
its  unorganized  but  voluntary  agencies.  We  must  learn  to 
see  Church  life  in  both,  nay,  to  perceive  in  their  union  and 
unanimous  co-operation  the  specifically  new  feature  of  the 
evangelical  form  of  the  Church,  which  is  at  the  ^same  time 
tending  towards  the  form  of  primitive  Christianity. 

3    Mode  of  Church  organization.     The  details  of  this  sub- 
ject belong  rather  to  practical  theology  and  ecclesiastical  law 
Ihey  depend  upon  the  organization  of  the  Church's  cardinal 
functions  of  self-manifestation,  self -propagation,  self-purifica- 
tion on  the  two  sides  of  life  and  knowledge  or  doctrine. 
A.  On  the  side  of  Life,  organization  has  respect  to— 
(a)  The  task  of  manifesting  the  Christian  life  :  (a)  m  public 
worship   by  preaching  and  the   administration  of  the   sacra- 
ments, by  sacred  music  and  hymns,  by  a  liturgy  and  an  order  of 
Divine  worship;  (/8)  in  Church  government,  which  7/icm^/cs^s 
itnion  in   individuals  and  in  large    circles;   and  (7)  m   the 
cliaconate  as  manifesting  the  agency  of  love. 

(h)  Self -purification  points  to  an  organization  of  Chwxh 
discipline  by  means  of  elders,  or  at  all  events  by  some  parti- 
cipation of  the  congregation. 

(c)  Self-propagation  needs  also  its  organization,  m  both  its 
intensive  and  extensive  agency;  (a)  Its  intensive  progresses 
effected  by  an  organization  of  the  legislative  function  with 
respect  to  Church  life.  This  embraces  a  Church  representa- 
tion in  synodal  form  according  to  the  doctrine  of  the  Lutheran 
and  Eeformed  Churches.  (/3)  The  organization  for  extensive 
propagation   includes   institutions    for  the   education    of   the 

1  According  to  a  marginal  note,  the  author  divides  the  voluntary  functions 
as  follows  :-l.  Self-manifestation,  (a)  Life,  voluntary  meetings  or  prayer. 
{h)  Knowledge,  voluntary  theological  meetings  and  literature  2.  Self-punjica- 
tion.  The  self-purifying  is  also  the  unifying  function,  for  the  impulse  to  unity 
in  Christendom  is  only  hindered  by  what  the  purifying  function  does  away  with. 
(a)  Family  discipline.  (6)  Moral  censure,  freely  passed  by  c  asses  from  a  nice 
though  strong  esprit  de  ccyrps-e.g.  by  the  military,  clerical,  and  acadennca 
classfs.  Both  these  are  directed  to  life,  (c)  Disseminat^or^  of  the  Scriptures 
(chiefly  directed  to  knowledge),  {d)  Inner  Mission  directed  to  both  life  and 
knowledge.     3.  Self -propagation.     Foreign  Missionary  Societies. 

2  Q 


610  §  83.    CHURCH  OEGANIZATION. 

young,  scJiools,  together  with  catechization  and  confirmation,  also. 
missions  for  the  conversion  of  the  non-Christian  nations. 

B.  On  the  ideal  side,  or  that  of  Doctrine,  the  organizations 
for  preservation  (manifestation),  purification  and  the  increase 
of  intelligence  are  the  following : — 

(a)  The  ohjective  organization  for  doctrine  is  the  synibol 
(creed),  the  system  of  doctrine,  and  the  regulations  relating 
to  teaching. 

(&)  The  subjective  organization  consists  of  the  teacliing  class, 
the  i\\Qo\ogicdl  faculties  and  theological  lite7xtture,  which  must 
all  be  active,  though  in  various  combinations,  in  the  self- 
manifestation,  self  -  purification,  extensive  propagation  and 
intensive  growth  of  the  Church.  Manifestation  devolves 
especially  upon  the  teaching  class,  the  clerisy  in  the  narrower 
sense ;  for  it  is  their  special  duty  to  advocate  and  make 
evident  all  that  is  latent  in  the  common  faith.  Literature, 
on  the  other  hand,  and  the  theological  faculties  should  exercise 
a  purifying  and  developing  agency  upon  the  ground  already 
won,  upon  the  system  of  doctrine.  The  collective  agency  of 
the  Church  with  respect  to  the  system  of  doctrine  must  seek 
to  combine  the  continuity  or  self-consistency  of  the  Church's 
consciousness,  i.e.  of  its  system  of  doctrine,  with  its  active 
progress. 

Collisions  may  arise  between  the  conservative,  and  the 
purifying  and  further  developing  activity.  Some  movement 
may,  in  its  supposed  acceleration  of  progress,  forsake  the  truths 
contained  in  the  Church's  creed,  and  seduce  others  from  them. 
That  which  is  extolled  by  some  as  an  advance,  may  be 
regarded  by  others  as  declension  or  apostasy  (Neology, 
Paleology).  Thus  parties  are  formed,  and  if  the  counter- 
poise to  party  -  spirit  should  be  lacking,  the  consequence 
would  be  the  dissolution  of  the  Church.  When  the  Church 
has  no  longer  a  definite  faith,  it  will  no  longer  have  a  right 
to  existence  as  a  separate  community  alongside  of  the  State. 
On  the  other  side,  the  necessity  of  movement  may  be  denied, 
and  it  may  be  ignored  that  the  most  perfect  words  of  the 
Church  are  still  not  equal  in  authority  to  the  words  of  Christ 
and  the  apostles,  but  imperfect.  The  result  is  that  the  creed 
of  the  Church,  placed  by  such  immobility  on  a  level  with 
Holy  Scripture,  then  becomes  its  guardian.     This  latter  pro- 


CIIUKCH  PAETIES.  611 

cess  leads  to  the  apotheosis  of  tradition  and  the  Church,  as 
the  former  does  to  the  apotheosis  of  the  subject.  The  union 
of  the  tendency  to  movement  and  the  tendency  to  continuity 
is  impossible  in  the  region  of  doctrine,  of  dogma  j3c?'  se.  It 
can  only  take  place  when  both,  in  opposition  to  intellectual 
orthodoxy  and  heterodoxy,  cease  to  regard  dogma  as  of 
primary  importance,  and  turn  from  it  to  simple  living  faith 
in  Christ.  For  this,  and  not  a  scientifically  formulated  body  of 
doctrine,  was  the  first  form  of  existence  taken  by  Christianity 
among  men.  The  faith  which  is  in  its  simplicity  expressed  by 
the  K^Tpvyixa  of  Christ,  is  the  vital  condition  of  all  true  Chris- 
tian theology.  It  is  by  such  faith  that  scientific  research  is 
qualified  for  a  deeper  comprehension  of  the  contents  of 
objective  Christianity  in  the  form  of  speculation.  By  means 
of  faith,  too,  will  such  scientific  research  be  regarded  as  a 
lawful  process  of  continuous  development,  and  will  manifest 
itself,  in  presence  both  of  the  logical  and  religious  conscience 
and  of  Holy  Scripture,  as  a  purer,  deeper  and  more  copious 
apprehension  of  the  evangelical  principle  itself. 

It  is  our  happy  case  that  preservation  and  manifestation, 
no  less  than  purification  and  continuous  development,  are  in 
every  respect  demanded  by  the  nature  of  the  Evangelical 
Church  itself,  in  virtue  of  the  fundamental  relation  between 
the  material  and  formal  sides  of  its  constituent  principle. 
The  Evangelical  Church  requires  that  we  should  be  faithful 
and  free,  making  these  qualities  permeate  each  other.  Past 
and  present  history  form  one  whole.  The  kingdom  of  God 
is  come,  but  it  is  also  to  come.  Let  no  reaching  towards  the 
future,  no  hope,  be  divorced  from  the  past.  For  God's  great 
moral  work  on  mankind  is  one,  is  woven  of  one  strong  texture, 
and  must  hold  ua  fast  in  the  world  of  faith  to  His  past  deal- 
ings in  the  history  of  revelation  and  of  the  Church.  Let  no 
faith  be  without  the  hope  which  looks  and  strives  onwards. 
And  finally,  let  love  be  the  ever  pulsating  soul  of  the  present. 
Let  love  in  combination  with  faith  and  hope  be  also  the 
motive  power  of  all  our  work,  in  the  great  and  new  duties 
placed  before  the  present  generation,  our  native  land  and  the 
Evangelical  Church. 


INDEX. 


Absolute  spliere  of  rigM,  301. 

Action,  definition  of,  129-132. 

Administration,  575. 

Aristocracy,  571. 

Aristotle's  notion  of  justice,  85. 

Art,  581  ;  relation  of,  to  Christianity, 
584  ;  to  the  civil  community  and  the 
State,  586. 

Arts,  the  plastic  and  poetic,  583. 

Ascetics,  405 ;  Eomish  and  Greek 
errors  concerning,  406;  permissibility 
of,  407. 

Association,  sexual,  304. 

Association,  tendencies  to,  183  ;  de- 
preciation and  over-estimation  of, 
185  ;  natural,  inadequate,  187. 

Augustine,  267. 

Beautiful,  the,  581. 

Bible,  the,  as  an  authority  in  ethics, 

45. 
Blood  relationship,  181. 

Capital  punishment,  577. 

Care  for  personal  honour,  452  ;  for  our 
physical  existence,  453  ;  of  the  body, 
456  ;  for  virtuous  happiness,  458  ; 
for  a  good  name,  487. 

Casuistry,  218, 

Celibacy,  536. 

Certitudo  salntis,  370 

Chastity,  467. 

Christ,  the  incarnate  good,  343  ;  the 
perfect  revelation  of  the  Divine  law, 
344  ;  the  all-embracing  virtue,  348  ; 
the  substitute  of  humanity,  349 ;  the 
princiiDle  of  the  kingdom  of  God, 
351  ;  the  principle  of  repentance  and 
righteousness,  353 ;  the  object  of 
faith,  366. 

Christian  love,  360  ;  wisdom  and  hope, 
361  ;  faith,  364. 

Christian  idea  of  God,  the  basis  of 
ethics,  51,  58. 

Christian  virtue,  in  the  individual, 
356  ;  faith  the  fundamental,  357. 

Christian  character,  the,  maintenance 
of,  401  ;  self-manifestation  of,  412. 


Christian  hope,  character  of,  386 ; 
object  of,  386. 

Christian  humour,  398. 

Christian  j^iety,  413. 

Cliristian  view  of  the  world,  388. 

Christian  and  philosophical  ethics, 
relation  of,  17,  24  ;  no  essential 
contradiction  between,  20;  nor  direct 
identity,  21  ff.  ;  mutual  dependence 
of,  25. 

Christianity,  4,  211. 

Church,  the,  idea  of,  591  ;  essential 
nature  of,  593  ;  cardinal  functions  of, 
598  ;  self-manifestation  of,  598,  607  ; 
self- propagation  of,  599,  607  ;  self- 
purification  of,  601,  607;  authority 
of,  in  ethics,  47. 

Church  discipline,  602  ;  Church  organi- 
zation, 604  ;  ethic  necessity  of,  605  ; 
mode  of,  609. 

Church  representation,  609. 

Churchly  mind,  the,  596. 

Civil  authority,  563  ;  Christian  obedi- 
ence to,  567. 

Cognition,  relation  of,  to  morality  and 
religion,  138. 

Cognitive  faculty,  the,  126. 

Collisions  in  the  sphere  of  property, 
470. 

Collisions  between  the  parties  of  con- 
servancy and  development,  610. 

Communities,  304. 

Comradeship,  the  analogue  of  friend- 
ship, 182. 

Concept  of  humanity,  the  Christian, 
447. 

Confession  of  Christian  faith,  443. 

Confessions,  different,  597. 

Connection  of  morality  and  religion, 
137. 

Conscience,  forms  of  its  manifestation, 
249  ;  imputation,  250  ;  judgment, 
251  ;  requital,  251  ;  an  erring, 
251. 

Conscience,  193  ;  not  the  ground  but 
the  perception  of  law,  196. 

Conscience,  doctrine  of,  225  ;  biblical, 
227  ;  positive,  229. 


612 


iiVDEX. 


613 


Conscience,  .and  moral  consciousness, 
231  ;  origin  of,  233  ;  not  based  on 
self-legislation,  235  ;  God's  voice, 
285  ;  stages  of,  237  ;  growth  of, 
238  ;  abnormal  state  of,  242  ;  appro- 
priates the  matter  of  experience,  245. 

Consilia  Eoangelica,  205. 

Constitution,  the,  569-572. 

Contemplation,  417  ;  essential  nature 
of,  418  ;  object  of,  419. 

Cosmopolitanism,  508. 

Counteraction  of  good  against  evil, 
325. 

Courage,  Christian,  397. 

Created  world,  the  source  of,  95. 

Culture,  true,  481. 

Darwinian  theory,  167. 

Democracy,  570. 

Determinism,  absolute  physical,  255  ; 
psychical,  261  ;  theological,  266. 

Determinism  and  Indetermiuism, 
255  ff. 

Diaconate,  the,  608. 

Dissimilarities,  adjustment  of,  509. 

Divine  agency,  continuous,  195. 

Divine  and  human  activity,  co-opera- 
tion of,  365. 

Division  of  labour,  the  analogue  of 
civil  society,  182. 

Divorce,  540  f. 

Dogmatics,  province  of,  4. 

Drama,  the,  584. 

Duelling,  454  ff. 

Duties, ' conflict  of,  213  f.,  217;  per- 
fect and  imperfect,  210. 

Duty,  notion  of,  9,  54. 

Duty  and  right,  221  ;  in  human 
relations,  223. 

Earthly  productions,  permanence  of, 

295  ;  in  the  final  consummation,  297. 
Elections,  571. 
Enjoyment  and  recreation,  461  ;  means 

of,  463. 
Eschatology,   ethical,     284 ;     different 

views  of,  284  ;  classical  view  of,  285  ; 

Christian  view  of,  283  ;  Reformation 

view  of,  286. 
Ethical  knowledge,  source  of,  43. 
Ethical  life  of  man,  5. 
Ethical  world,  God's  ideal  of  the,  96  ; 

nature  a  necessary  factor  of,  97. 
Ethics  an  independent  department,  5. 
Ethics,  history  of,  works  on  the,  28, 

42  ;  system  of,  3. 
Eudaemonism,  321. 
Evil,  notion  of,  13. 

Faith  and  hope,  385. 

Faith  necessarily  produces  love,  872. 

Faith    in    Christ    morally    necessary, 


337  ;    not   an   act  of  caprice,   339  ; 

tlie   fundamental   Christian    virtue, 

357. 
False  forms  of  love  to  God,  374, 
Family,    the,    549  ;   an  image   of  the 

kingdom  of  God,  550. 
Feelings,  the,  124. 
Formative  principle,  the,  107. 
Forms    of    virtue,     classification    and 

analysis  of,  359. 
Freedom,  193,  209,  253,  268  ;  positive 

doctrine   of,  273  ;   biblical   doctrine 

of,    275  ;    stages  in   its   realization., 

278  ;  theological,  281. 
Freedom    and    conscience,    union    of, 

371. 
Freedom,    indispensable    to    progress, 

336. 
Friendship,    science,    and  art  on   the 

stage  of  right,  310. 
Friendships,  family,  514. 

Giving  and  receiving,  right,  511. 

Gnosis,  383. 

God  and  the  world,  analogy  between, 

97. 
God-man,    the,     necessity    of,     334  ; 

uniqueness   of,    338  ;    absolute  and 

permanent  significance  of,  344. 
God's  nature  the  source  of  moral  law, 

196. 
Good,  the,  as  realized  in  Christianity, 

343  ;  science  of,  7,  54. 
Gospel,  effects  of,  368. 
Grammar  schools,  589. 

Habits,  401. 

Heathenism,  322  ;  development  of  e\'il 

in,  323  ;  degeneration  of  science  in, 

323. 
Heathen  world,  apotheosis  of  the  State 

in,   323  ;  consciousness  of  guilt  in, 

327  ;  philosoiihy  in,  328. 
Hebraism  and  Christianity,  247. 
Hebrew,  consciousness  of  guilt,   327  ; 

settled  moral  ideas,  329  ;  Messianic 

hope. 
Household,     the,     the      fundamental 

moral   community,   522  ;    extension 

of,  by  friends,  guests,  and  servants, 

522. 
Human  instinct,  deficiency  of,  189. 
Human    nature,    unifying    tendencies 

in,  178. 
Humanity,  320, 

InEAL,  the  moral,  283  ;  biblical  doc- 
trine of,  292  ;  contents  of,  293  ;  reali- 
zation of,  298  ;  synopsis  of,  300. 

Identity,  man's  consciousness  of. 

Independence,  Christian  endeavour 
after,  485, 


G14 


INDEX. 


In  determinism,  257  ;  absolute,  259  ; 
of  indifference,  260,  263  f. 

Individuality,  141  ;  necessity  of,  142  ; 
ethical  significance  of,  143  ;  perma- 
nence of,  145  ;  general  nature  of, 
1 45  ;  different  views  of,  considered, 
147  ;  genesis  of,  149. 

Individuality  and  likeness,  antithesis 
of.  111. 

Intercession,  507. 

Jewish  forms  of  siu,  324-5. 
Judicial  functions,  575. 
Justice,  history  of  the  notion  of,  81  ; 
theological  conception  of,  91. 

Kant  on  the  immoral,  14. 
Kant  on  moral  feeling,  139. 
Kant's  categorical  impei'ative,  199. 
Kant's  critical  system,  4. 
Kingdom    of   God,  the,     moral    com- 
munities in,  516. 
Knowledge,  Christian,  2. 

Law,  191  ;  binding  character  of,  196  ; 
necessity  of,  198,  203  ;  absoluteness 
of,  198,  203;  universality  of,  201, 
203. 

Law  or  right,  stage  of,  301;  imperfec- 
tions of,  311  ;  cannot  prevent  sin, 
312  ;  insufficient  even  with  respect 
to  the  State,  314  ;  with  reference  to 
sin,  316. 

Law,  moral,  erroneous  views  of,  refuted, 
202. 

Law,  standpoint  of,  called  by  Eabbis 
a  new  creation,  302. 

Legal  standpoint,  imperfection  of,  311. 

Legislation,  560,  572. 

Leibnitz  on  the  notion  of  justice,  86. 

Leibnitz's  theodicy,  388. 

Lies,  white,  490  ;  degi-ee  of  guilt  in, 
491. 

Love,  relation  between  communicative 
and  receptive,  379  ;  the  unity  of  the 
productive  virtues,  381. 

Love,  the  stage  of,  332. 

Love  the  essence  of  God's  moral  nature, 
69  ;  three  views  of,  69 ;  distinction 
between,  and  righteousness,  74  ;  as 
self-devotion,  92  ;  amor  concupis- 
centice,  70,  374  ;  complaceniia, 
70,  374  ;  henevolenticB,  71,  374. 

Love  to  one's  neighbour,  504  ff.  ;  care 
for  his  spiritual  welfare,  517  ;  be- 
tween brothers  and  sisters,  552. 

Love  as  the  opposite  of  selfishness, 
378. 

Man's  physical  endowment,  113  ;  his 
finiteness,  113-117  ;  his  bodily 
organism,  118  ;  his  hand,  118  ;  voice. 


119  ;  his  means  of  self-preservation 
and  reproduction,  121  ;  psychical 
element  of  his  moral  constitution, 
122  ;  his  rational  constitution,  134  ; 
his  capacity  for  morality  and  religion, 
135. 

Marriage,  scriptural  conception  of, 
523  ;  history  of  ideas  concerning,  in 
Christian  times,  525  ;  socialistic  and 
communistic  theories  of,  529  ;  Hegel 
and  Schleiermacher's  views  on,  529  ; 
indissoluble,  530-539  ;  its  physical 
side,  531  ;  a  school  of  virtue,  532  ; 
contraction  of,  535  ;  relation  of 
State  and  Church  to,  546 ;  civil, 
547. 

Materialism,  doctrine  of,  101-103  ; 
an  inadequate  hypothesis,  103;  denies 
human  freedom,  105. 

Method,  42  ;  the  descriptive  and  the 
psychological,  49. 

Modification  of  the  idea  of  property  by 
Christianity,  473. 

Monarcliy,  571  ;  hereditary  preferable 
to  elective,  57l. 

Monogamy,  539. 

Moral  feeling,  the,  139,  193  ;  relation 
of,  to  freedom,  141. 

Moral  law,  oneness  of,  213. 

Moral  ideas,  confusion  of,  among 
heathen,  244. 

Moral  choice,  possibility  and  necessity 
of,  275. 

Moral  evil,  universality  of,  321. 

Morality,  meaning  of,  6,  12  ;  formal 
aspect  of,  13  ;  essential  to  the  Divine 
Being,  61  ;  a  necessary  tliought,  67  ; 
supremacy  of,  in  God,  67 ;  nature  of, 
in  God,  68  ;  the  idea  of,  tends  to  ex- 
istence, 62;  not  an  arbitrary  creation, 
63;  of  the  very  essence  of  God's  being, 
64  ;  positive  nature  of,  72  ;  relation 
of,  to  religion,  137  ;  relation  of  tem- 
perament to,  161. 

National  distinctions,  importance  of, 

173. 
Natural  theology,  24. 
Nature,  man's  dominion  over,  179. 
New   personality,    the,   in  relation  to 

itself,  445. 
Nitzsch's  system  of  Christian  doctrine, 

3. 
Nomadic  life,  179. 

Oath,  idea  of  an,  492  ;  a  covenant  with 
God,  493  ;  a  contract  between  men, 
493  ;  a  religious  confession,  404  ; 
New  Testament  passages  with  regard 
to,  494. 

Oaths,  492. 

Obedience,  551. 


INDEX. 


G15 


Official   organization   of    the   Church, 

606  ;  limits  of,  607. 
Optimism,  390  ;  the  two  forms  of,  391  ; 

the  joy  of,  397. 

Party  spirit,  508. 

Passions,  the,  465. 

Permissible  action,  theory  of,  213. 

Personal  character  of  love,  377. 

Pessimism,  389  ;  tlie  true  forms  of, 
392  ;  within  the  Church,  393;  pain 
of,  395. 

Petition  and  intercession,  423. 

Philosophy  not  necessarily  non-Chris- 
tian, 24. 

Plato's  notion  of  justice,  83. 

Politics  and  religion,  561. 

Polygamy,  540. 

Ponerology,  ethical,  316. 

Powers,  the,  that  be,  565. 

Prayer,  422  ;  forms  of,  428  f.  ;  times 
of,  430  f. 

Predestination,  267. 

Predeterminism  of  freedom,  270. 

Pride,  lovelessness  of,  378. 

Property,  309. 

Property,  unequal  distribution  of,  475. 

Public  worshij),  fellowship  in,  595, 
596. 

Punishment,  right  of,  306-308. 

Purpose  and  worth,  notions  of,  16. 

Race,  differences  of,  character  and  limit 

of,  164. 
Places  and  nationalties,  162  ;  as  related 

to  temperament,  171. 
Redemption,  man's  need  of,  and  capacity 

for,  331. 
Relation  of  the  natural  to  the  spiritual, 

109. 
Relation    of   God's  ethical   and  non- 
ethical  attributes,  65. 
Relations  of  men  to  men,  180. 
Religious  zeal,  441  ;  limit  of,  444. 
Religious  meetings,  608. 
Reverence  and  love,  415. 
Right,  material  and  formal,  difference 

between,  560  ;  public,  563. 
Right  as  universal  will,  306. 
Ritschl  on  justice,  89. 
Rothe  on  the  moral  ideal,  289. 
Rudimentary   civilisation,    defects    of, 

183. 
Rulers  and  subjects,  563. 
Rural  life,  186. 

SCHLETERMACHEK',  215,  216. 

Schleiermacher Quoted,    3,    199,   268, 

287. 
Schleiermacher's  philosophische  Elhik, 

15. 

Science,  587. 


Secondary  sphere  of  right,   303  ;   im- 
perfection  of  the   stage    of  law   in 
the,  313. 
Self-activity  of  the  Christian,  403. 
Self-assertion  and    self- manifestation, 

484. 
Self-assertion,  the  Divine,  78. 
Self-defence,  308. 
Self-inspection,  421. 
Self-love  and  social  love  in  relation  to 

love  to  God,  376. 
Self-love,    Christian,    445,     447;    its 

nature,  449. 
Self-love  essential  to  self-impartation, 

77  ;  of  God,  94. 
Self-love   with   respect   to   the   mind, 

480. 
Self-manifestation,  tlie  Divine,  80. 
Self-preservation,  178. 
Self-surrender  to  Christ,  369. 
Sensuality,  321, 
Servants,  553. 
Sex,  difference  of,  150-155, 
Sexual  love,  181. 

Sin,  not  a  mere  defect,  318  ;  shows  the 
insufficiency  of  the  legal  standpoint, 
318 ;  actual  existence  of,  in  humanity, 
320. 
Social  intercourse,  305,  514. 
Socialism  and  communism,  478. 
Soul,  the,  as  activity  and  as  a  state,  133. 
Soul's,  the,  three  forms   of  existence, 

123. 
Species,  human,  unity  of  the,  169, 
Species,  theory  of,  165. 
State,    the,    305  ;    the  community  of 
right    points   to    the    higher    com- 
munity,  the  Church,  316  ;   Rothe's 
view     of,     618  ;   idea  of,   554  ;    its 
dependence  upon  religion,  556  ;  prin- 
ciple of  the  idea  of  right,  558 ;  re- 
lation of,  to  its  future,  and  to  other 
States,  578  ;   Christian  character  of, 
580. 
Strife,  513. 
Sunday,   435    ff.  ;    foundation   of  the 

Christian,  438. 
Supererogatory  works,  207. 
Supralapsarianism,  268. 
Syllabus  of  the  system,  48 ;  of  Part  I. , 

112. 
Systematic  theology  presupposes  faith, 
2. 

Talents,  the,  174;  identity  of,  183; 
democratic  and  aristocratic  concep- 
tion of,  175, 

Temperament,  the  phlegmatic,  158 ; 
the  sanguine,  158  ;  the  melancholic, 
159;  the  choleric,  159. 

Temperaments,  the,  155;  their  relation 
to  morality,  161 


61G 


INDEX. 


Thankfulness  towards  men,  512. 
Thanksgiving  and  praise,  427. 
Tribal  habits  and  customs,  182. 
True  culture,  481. 
Truthfulness,  487. 

Universities,  589. 

Virtue,  doctrine  of,  10,  54;  means  of, 
409;  religious,  410  ;  moral,  410. 


Virtuous  ownership,  469. 

Virtuous  purity  and  beauty,  464 ;  their 

connection,  464,  467. 
Virtuous  stability,  483. 
Vocation,  498 ;  its  universality,  500 ; 

choice  of,  501  f. 
Voluntary  agencies,  607. 

Wisdom,  Christian,  .382. 
AVorld    designed    for    moralit}',    and 
morality  for  the  world,  93. 


THE  END. 


/ 


M 


^^R  8  -   '^io^