Skip to main content

Full text of "Theories of parallelism; an historical critique"

See other formats


I 


THE  LIBRARY 

OF 

THE  UNIVERSITY 
OF  CALIFORNIA 

LOS  ANGELES 


1 


THEORIES 

OF 

PARALLELISM 


CAMBRIDGE    UNIVERSITY   PRESS 

FETTER   LANE,    E.G. 
C.  F.  CLAY,  MANAGER 


ioo,  PRINCES  STREET 

Berlin:    A.  ASHER  AND  CO. 

H.eip>ts:    F-   A-  BROCKHAUS 

&m  Iforh:    G.  P.  PUTNAM'S  SONS^ 

Bombap.  anU  Calcutta:    MACMILLAN  AND  CO.,  LTD. 

lotrton:   H.  K.  LEWIS,  .36,  GOWER  STREET,  W.C. 


AH  rights  reserved 


THEORIES 

OF 

PARALLELISM 

AN    HISTORICAL    CRITIQUE 


BY 


WILLIAM    BARRETT    FRANKLAND,    M.A. 

SOMETIME    FELLOW    OF    CLARE    COLLEGE,    CAMBRIDGE: 
VICAR    OF    WRAWBY 


Cambridge : 

at    the    University    Press 
1910 


..  .s. 

-  1  o  ¥  r 


PRINTED   BY  jofȣ  CLAY,   M.A. 
AT  THE   UNIVERSITY   PRESS 


IDs  ic  J 


% 


Mathemitfoat 
Sciences 
Libraiy 


IN    PIAM    MEMOEIAM 
ELIZABETHAE    DE    BURGH 


801780 

ilATIlEUATJCS 


CONTENTS 

PAGE 

APOLOGY .        .  vii 

INTRODUCTION xi 

THEORIES  OF  PARALLELISM  : 

B.C. 

300  EUCLID 1 

80  POSIDONIUS 4 

70  GEMINUS  (?  AGANIS) 5 

A.D. 

150  PTOLEMY 6 

450  PROCLUS 7 

900  ANARITIUS  (AN-NAIRIZI)        .        .-      .        .        .        .  10 

1000  GERBERT  (POPE  SYLVESTER  II) 10 

1250  NASREDDIN  (NASIRADDIN  AT-Tusi)       ....  11 

1570   BlLLINGSLEY  .                       12 

1574  CLAVIUS 13 

1604  OLIVER 14 

1621  SAVILE 15 

1654  TACQUET        .........  15 

1655  HOBBES                          1 16 

1663  WALLIS 17 

1679  LEIBNIZ 19 

1680  DA  BITONTO    .        .        .        .        .        .        .        .        .  19 

1733  SACCHERI       .....       ^       ...  20 

1756  SIMSON  ...........  23 

1766  LAMBERT 24 

1778  BERTRAND 26 

1795  PLAYFAIR 30 

1796  LAPLACE 31 


x  Contents 

A.D.  PAGE 

1799  GAUSS 32 

1803  CARNOT 35 

1804  W.  BOLTAI .        .  36 

1809  THIBAUT 37 

1825  TAURINUS 37 

1832  J.  BOLYAI 39 

1833  LEGENDRE 40 

1840  LOBACHEWSKI 42 

1844  MEIKLE 44 

1850  BOUNIAKOWSKI 45 

1854  KIEMANN 46 

1859  CAYLEY 47 

1866  VON  HELMHOLTZ    ....    :    ....  47 

1868  BELTRAMI       .                48 

1870  CLIFFORD 48 

1871  KLEIN 49 

1877  NEWCOMB 50 

1895  DODGSON 52 

FIRST  ADDITIONAL  NOTE  : 

ANALYTICAL  GEOMETRY  FOR  THE  METABOLIC  HYPOTHESES  .  53 

SECOND  ADDITIONAL  NOTE  : 

PLANETARY  MOTION  FOR  THE  METABOLIC  HYPOTHESES       .  62 

POSTSCRIPT  70 


INTRODUCTION 

A  BRIEF  preliminary  investigation  of  the  bases  of  Geometry 
is  necessary  in  order  to  furnish  the  means  of  testing  the  various 
Theories  of  Parallelism  with  which  we  shall  deal.  Knowing, 
for  instance,  whether  the  enunciation  of  a  proposition  is  correct 
or  incorrect,  we  know  where  most  especially  to  search  for 
mistakes  of  reasoning;  and  a  careful  study  of  the  following 
Introduction  should  therefore  make  it  a  pleasurable  task  to 
criticise  the  work  of  the  earlier  Geometers.  It  will  be  observed 
that  this  short  Introduction  is  not  Euclidean  in  style  nor 
elementary  in  method ;  nor  again  is  it  in  itself  thoroughly 
complete  and  satisfactory.  On  the  one  hand,  the  student  in- 
terested in  the  future  rather  than  the  past  of  Geometry  will 
turn  to  the  masterly  summaries  in  Dr  Whitehead's  two  tracts 
(The  Axioms  of  Projective  Geometry,  1906 ;  The  Axioms  of 
Descriptive  Geometry,  1907 ;  Cambridge).  On  the  other  hand, 
a  strictly  Euclidean  exposition  of  the  Fundamental  Theorem 
of  Geometry  has  been  given  in  the  Appendix  to  Euclid  Book  I 
with  a  Commentary  (Cambridge,  1902);  and  the  line  of  thought 
projected  by  Meikle,  Kelland  and  Chrystal  has  been  success- 
fully followed  out  by  Dr  Manning  (Non-Euclidean  Geometry, 
Boston,  1901).  However,  the  ensuing  discussion  will  supply 
what  is  indispensable  for  critical  purposes  in  this  book.  Some 
things  in  it,  and  in  the  Additional  Notes  at  the  end,  may 
perhaps  be  called  original  work.  Biographical  information  will 
be  found  in  the  pages  of  Mr  Rouse  Ball's  Histoi'y  of  Mathe- 
matics or  Dr  Cantor's  Geschichte  der  Mathematik. 

Without  further  preface  let  us  assume  that  straight  lines 
are  freely  applicable  to  themselves  and  to  one  another;   and 


xii  Introduction 

that  there  is  a  plane  in  which  they  are  freely  raoveable  ;  and 
let  us  investigate  the  parallelism  of  such  straight  lines  in  such 
an  even  plane.  The  principal  theorem  thus  obtained  may  be 
allowed  to  accredit  itself  after  the  fashion  in  which  the  diamond 
approves  itself  the  hardest  stone.  Whatever  defects  our  proof 
of  it  may  possess,  its  credentials  have  been  shown  by  Beltrami 
to  be  irreproachable  (below,  page  48). 

This  Principal  Theorem  of  Plane  Geometry  is  as  follows  : 
If  two  polygons  are  called  equal  in  area  when  one  can  be 
dissected  into  triangles  which  can  be  pieced  together  to  cover 
the  other  exactly  ;  and  if,  in  the  uncertainty  (apart  from  pre- 
judice) about  the  angle-sum  of  any  triangle  being  precisely  TT, 
we  define  the  divergence  of  a  polygon  having  n  sides  to  be  the 
difference  between  its  angle-sum  and  (n  —  2)  TT  ;  then  the  area 
of  any  polygon  is  proportional  to  its  divergence  (Hilbert). 

For  a  proof  of  this,  consider  first  this  Lemma  : 
In  any  compact  agglomeration  of  rectilinear  cells  in  the 
plane,  if  v  is  the  number  of  the  cells,  a-  the  number  of  vertices, 
and  «r  the  number  of  walls,  then  a-  +  v  =  «r  +  1. 

For  if  a  broken  line  of  £  rectilinear  pieces  be  introduced 
to  connect  two  vertices  of  any  cell,  a-  is  increased  by  £—  1, 
v  by  1,  and  or  by  £  This  being  always  true,  and  the  equation 
a  +  v  =  -cr  +  1  holding  good  for  the  external  boundary,  this 
same  equation  is  always  true. 

Hence  it  follows  that  the  divergence  of  the  boundary  of  the 
agglomeration  is  equal  to  the  sum  of  the  divergences  of  the 
individual  cells  composing  it.  For  if  S  be  the  angle-sum  oi 
the  external  boundary,  supposed  a  polygon  of  n  sides;  and  ii 
Si,  s%  ...  sv  are  the  angle-sums  of  the  v  cells,  of  which  the  sides 
number^,  pz  ...  p,  respectively,  then 
sum  of  divergences  of  cells 


=  S  +  (<r  -  n)  2-7T  -  ir£pv  + 

=  S  +  (o-  -  n  +  i/)  2?r  -  TT  (2*r  -  w) 

=  8-(n-2)7r 

=  divergence  of  external  boundary  of  agglomeration, 


•   Introduction  xiii 

Thus  polygons  of  equal  area  have  equal  divergence. 
Hence  with  any  area  is  associated  a  divergence.  Let  A  be 
the  area  associated  with  the  divergence  8.  We  may  then 
write  A=/(8);  and  as  there  is  no  reason  to  doubt  the 
applicability  of  Euclidean  Geometry  to  infinitesimal  areas, 
A  is  a  continuous  function  of  8.  But,  considering  an  agglo- 
meration of  two  cells  only,  with  divergences  8  and  e, 


Differentiating  for  8, 

/'(S  +  e)=/'<S). 

Hence  /'  (8)  is  a  constant,  the  same  for  every  polygon,  say 
A.     Therefore,  by  integration  for  8, 


where  A  and  B  are  constant  over  the  whole  plane. 
I.e.     &  =  A8  +  B. 

But  when  A  -»-  0,  §  -»•  0  also  ;  for  the  geometry  of  an 
infinitesimal  area  can  be  accepted  as  Euclidean. 

Thus  A  =  4  8, 

i.e.  Area  is  proportional  to  Divergence. 

According  to  the  value  of  A  for  the  plane,  there  are  thus 
suggested  three  Hypotheses  of  equal  rank,  for  A  may  be 
positive,  or  negative,  or  even  (in  the  extreme  case)  infinite. 
In  these  cases  8  >  0,  8  <  0,  or  8  =  0,  throughout  the  plane. 
Accordingly  the  Geometry  of  the  Plane  may  be  either  Elliptic, 
or  Hyperbolic,  or  Parabolic  ;  and  for  these  three  mutually 
exclusive  Hypotheses,  the  angle-sum  of  a  triangle  is  greater 
than,  or  is  less  than,  or  is  equal  to  TT,  respectively.  It  may 
be  said  that  the  irrefragable  demonstration  of  this  Theorem  is 
the  greatest  triumph  ever  won  by  Geometrical  Science. 

We  can  now  prove  that  for  the  elliptic,  parabolic,  and 
hyperbolic  hypotheses,  there  are  no,  one  and  two  parallels,  re- 
spectively, to  any  given  straight  line  through  any  given  point. 
For  let  M  be  the  given  point,  and  BB'  the  given  straight  line. 


xiv  Introduction 

Draw  MN  perpendicular  to  BB',  and  AM  A'  perpendicular  to 
MN.  Within  the  angle  AMN  let  a  straight  line  through  M, 
meeting  NB  in  P,  begin  to  rotate  from  MN  towards  MA. 
Then, 

(i)    for  the  elliptic  hypothesis,  there  are  no  parallels. 

For  the  area  of  the  triangle  MPN  is  proportional  to  the 
divergence  of  that  triangle  ;   say, 

-  TT) 


so  that  /.MPN>  /.AMP;  and  as  MP  rotates  further,  and 
A  MPN  increases  in  area,  the  difference  Z  MPN  —  Z  AMP 
increases.  Hence  when  /.AMP  reaches  zero,  /.MPN  is  finite 
still;  and  therefore  MP  continues  to  intersect  NB,  even  in 
the  position  MA.  Thus  for  the  elliptic  hypothesis  there  are 
no  parallels. 
Next, 

(ii)    for  the   parabolic  hypothesis,   there  is   one   duplex 
parallel. 

For  in  this  special  case  the  divergence  of  the  triangle  MPN 
is  zero.  Thus  Z  MPN  =  Z  A  MP  ;  and  as  MP  rotates  into  the 
position  MA,  and  Z  AMP  decreases  to  zero,  so  also  does  Z  MPN 
pari  passu  decrease  to  zero.  Therefore  MA  is  parallel  to  NB 
(see  Corollary  below).  And  likewise  MA'  is  parallel  to  NB'. 
But  AM  A'  is  one  straight  line;  and  so  there  is  one  duplex 
parallel  for  the  parabolic  hypothesis. 

Lastly, 

(iii)    for  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis,  there  are  two  parallels. 
For  the  area  of  the  triangle  MPN  is  proportional  to  the 
divergence  of  that  triangle  ;   say, 

AMPN=K*(7r- 


so  that  Z  MPN  <z  AMP;  and  as  MP  rotates,  and  A  MPN 
increases  in  area,  the  difference  Z  AMP  -  Z  MPN  increases. 
Hence  before  Z  AMP  reaches  zero,  Z  MPN  has  vanished  ; 
and  therefore  (see  Corollary  below)  MP  is  parallel  to  NB  in 


Introduction  xv 

some  position  MH  within  the  angle  NMA.  Similarly  there  is 
another  distinct  parallel  MH'  within  the  angle  NMA'.  Thus 
for  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis  there  are  two  parallels. 

To  strengthen  this  argument,  we  choose  a  suitable  definition 
of  parallelism,  and  deduce  a  Corollary  in  the  manner  of 
Lobachewski, 

DEFINITION.  A  parallel  to  a  given  straight  line  through  a 
given  point  is  that  straight  line  which  never  intersects  the 
given  straight  line,  however  far  both  are  produced  in  the 
direction  of  parallelism,  whereas  any  other  straight  line  drawn 
through  the  given  point,  and  inside  the  parallel,  does  intersect 
the  given  straight  line. 

COROLLARY.  The  angle  MPN  decreases  to  zero  as  MP 
becomes  parallel  to  NB. 

We  will  show  that  if  e  be  any  assigned  angle,  however 
small,  then  Z  MPN  <  e,  before  MP  reaches  the  position  of 
parallelism.  Let  MN  be  perpendicular  to  JBNB',  as  usual,  and 
let  MH  be  as  before  the  parallel  to  NB  through  M ;  and  let 
MP  make  with  MH  on  the  inside  an  angle  e.  Then,  by  the 
definition  of  parallelism,  MP  meets  NB,  say  at  P.  Along  NB 
measure  off  PQ  =  PM.  Then  MQ  is  a  straight  line  meeting 
NB,  and  lying  within  the  angle  PMH.  But  by  an  indubitable 
proposition,  Z  MQP  =  z  QMP  <  e.  Thus  a  straight  line  MQ 
has  been  found  such  that  Z  MQN  <  e,  however  small  e  may  be. 

This  Corollary  is  of  course  intended  for  the  parabolic  and 
hyperbolic  hypotheses  only. 

With  whatever  defects,  this  discussion  of  Parallelism  is 
sufficient  in  this  place.  It  is  necessary  also  to  observe  care- 
fully the  nature  of  equidistants  to  a  given  straight  line.  So 
far  from  equidistants  being  identical  with  parallels,  equidistants 
are  not  rectilinear,  save  in  the  infinitely  special  case  of  the 
parabolic  hypothesis. 

Consider  two  straight  lines  MA,  NB  which  possess  a 
common  perpendicular  MN.  Let  a  perpendicular  to  NB  at 
any  point  Q  meet  M A  in  P.  Then  the  angle  MPQ  is  not 


xvi  Introduction 

right,  except  for  the  parabolic  hypothesis ;  for  the  ellipti 
or  hyperbolic  hypotheses,  it  is  obtuse  or  acute  respectively 
Furthermore,  as  Q  moves  along  NB,  and  area  PQNM  increases 
the  angle  MPQ  continually  increases,  decreases,  or  remains  th 
same,  according  as  the  elliptic,  hyperbolic,  or  parabolic  hype 
thesis  holds  good,  respectively.  It  will  also  be  useful  to  prov 
(as  in  the  Appendix  to  Euclid  Book  I  with  a  Commentary)  tha 
the  length  of  the  perpendicular  PQ  decreases,  increases,  c 
remains  the  same,  respectively. 

PROPOSITION.  If  AM,  BN  are  straight  lines,  to  which  MN  i 
a  common  perpendicular ;  and  as  Q  moves  in  NB  from  N  to  1 
PQ  is  always  drawn  perpendicular  to  NB  to  meet  M A  in  jP 
then  according  as  the  elliptic,  parabolic,  or  hyperbolic  hype 
thesis  is  maintained,  the  length  of  PQ  continually  decrease! 
remains  the  same,  or  increases,  respectively. 

For  suppose  PiQi,  P2Q2,  PSQ3  to  be  three  positions  of  P( 
as  Q  moves  from  N  towards  B.  If  P2Q2  is  greater  than  P^ 
and  P3Q3,  or  again  if  P2Q2  is  less  than  both  the  others,  contrar 
to  the  enunciation,  then  it  will  be  possible  to  find  two  position 
of  PQ,  namely,  pq  between  PjQt  and  P2Q2,  and  p'q'  bet  wee 
P2Q2  and  P8Q3,  such  that  pq  and  p'q'  are  of  equal  lengt 
(Principle  of  Continuity). 

Consider  now  nothing  else  but  the  quadrilateral  pqq'p'  i 
which  angles  q,  q  are  right,  and  the  sides  pq,  p'q'  equal.  Bisec 
qq'  in  k,  and  draw  kh  perpendicular  to  qq'  to  meet  pp'  in  ) 
Fold  the  quadrilateral  pqq'p'  about  hk,  so  that  kq  covers  kq 
Then  qp  covers  q'p'.  And  since  h  and  p  have  now  the  position 
h  and  p',  hp  covers  hp'.  Hence  the  angles  khp  and  khp'  ar 
equal;  and  therefore  the  angle  khp  is  right. 

Hence  the  divergence  of  the  quadrilateral  MhkN  is  zero 
and  therefore  the  area/divergence  constant  is  infinite;  and  s 
the  geometry  of  the  plane  is  parabolic,  and  all  the  perpen 
diculars  PQ  equal,  contrary  to  supposition.  Thus  in  th 
elliptic  and  hyperbolic  hypotheses  the  length  of  PQ  continuall 
decreases  and  increases,  respectively. 

It  is  in  fact  evident  that  PQ  decreases  for  the  ellipti 
hypothesis,  for  at  finite  distance  along  NB  it  vanishes.  An 


Introduction  xvii 

it  should  be  noted,  that  for  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis  PQ 
becomes  infinite  at  finite  distance  from  MN  \  indeed,  con- 
siderations of  area  and  divergence  suggest  that  Z  MPQ  must 
presently  vanish.  If  b,  x,  y  are  the  lengths  of  MN,  NQ,  QP, 
then  for  the  elliptic  hypothesis, 

y  x  L      b 

tan  j-  =  cos  r  tan  T  ; 


and  for  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis, 

tanl 
so  that  y  is  infinite  for 


tanh  -C  =  cosh  j=.  tanh  -^ 
K.  Ji.  J\. 


cosh  -jf.  =  coth  -~ . 

A  /\ 

To  these  results  may  be  added  the  following,  of  which 
satisfactory  proof  will  be  found  in  Dr  Manning's  Non-Euclidean 
Geometry : 

If  two  straight  lines  OP,  OQ  enclose  an  angle  /3,  aod  if  PQ 
is  perpendicular  to  OQ  at  Q,  then  writing  x,  y  for  the  lengths 
OQ,  QP  respectively, 

for  the  elliptic  hypothesis : 

7/  3C 

tan  £  =  sin  T  tan  /8 ; 
and  for  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis : 

'II  IP 

tanh  -^  =  sinh  -~  tan  /3. 

A  A 

The  parabolic  metric  is  obtained  by  "making  k  (or  K)  infinite." 

Comparing  the  equation  of  an  equidistant 

y  =  b 

with  the  former  pair  of  equations  above,  it  at  once  appears 
that  for  the  elliptic  and  hyperbolic  hypotheses,  equidistants  are 
not  rectilinear.  In  these  two  general  cases,  the  equidistant  is 
a  curve,  convex  and  concave,  respectively,  to  its  base. 

It  will  also  be  convenient  to  add  the  formulae  connecting 


XV111 


Introduction 


the  sides  a,  b,  c  and  the  angles  A,  B,  C  of  a  triangle  right- 
angled  at  A  : 


ELLIPTIC  HYPOTHESIS 


a  be 

cos  T  =  cos  T  cos  T 


.    o        .    a   .     „ 
sin  r  =  sin  T  sin  B 
k  k 


tan  T  =  tan  T  cos  B 
k  k 

b       .    c 

tan  T  =  sin  T  tan  .B 
k  k 


cos  B  =  cos  -  sin 

ft 


HYPERBOLIC  HYPOTHESIS 


,   a  .    b       .    c 

cosh  —  =  cosh  ^.cosh  — 

A  K.  K 


sinh  —  =  sinh  —  sin  B 
K.  K. 

tanh  -^  =  tanh  —  cos  B 
A  K. 

b  c 

tanh  —  =  sinh  —  tan  B 
K.  K. 


cos  B  =  cosh  —  sin  C 
A 


These  formulae  contain  the  whole  of  the  metric  of  the 
non-Euclidean  geometries.  Thus,  if  the  angle  B  diminish  to 
zero,  the  angle  of  parallelism  C  is  determined  by  the  last 
formula  on  the  right: 

1  =  cosh      sin  C. 


It  will  be  observed  that  the  first  formulae  correspond  to  the 
Pythagorean  Theorem  (Euc.  I.  47). 

With  these  preliminaries,  we  may  now  commence  the  task 
of  criticising  Theories  of  Parallelism  in  the  order  of  their 
appearance.  Further  developments  of  this  brief  Introduction 
will  be  found  in  the  First  Additional  Note  at  the  end  of  the 
volume. 


EUCLID 


Elements  of  Geometry,  B.C.  300. 

Venerated  in  Geometry  more  than  Aristotle  in  Philosophy, 
the  Elementist  has  enjoyed  a  fame  excelled  by  none  in  the 
domain  of  pure  knowledge.  This  well-merited  fame  has  un- 
fortunately hampered  and  impeded  research  into  the  Science  of 
Space,  and  the  more  so  on  account  of  the  strange  transmutations 
of  the  text  of  the  Elements,  which  have  cloked  the  weaknesses 
of  Euclid's  method.  This  strange  confusion  as  to  first  principles 
is  displayed  by  the  table  below : 


Editor 

Date 

Place 

Postulates 

Axioms 

EUCLID 

B.C.  300 

Alexandria 

5 

5 

Proclus 

A.D.  450 

Athens 

5 

5 

Grynaeus 

1533 

Basle 

3 

11 

Billingsley 

1570 

London 

6 

9 

Gregory 

1703 

Oxford 

3 

12 

Playfair 

1795 

Edinburgh 

3 

11 

Peyrard 

1814 

Paris 

6 

9 

Todhunter 

1862 

London 

3 

12 

Referring  to  Dr  Heath's  magnificent  edition  of  the  Elements 
(Cambridge,  1908)  for  detailed  information,  we  will  reproduce 
here  Euclid's  first  principles  as  he  himself  laid  them  down : 

(A)     Necessary  Concessions: 

(1)     Let  it  be  conceded  that  from  every  point  to  every 
point  a  straight  line  can  be  drawn ; 


F.  E. 


1 


2  Theories  of  Parallelism 

(2)  And  a  limited  straight  line  can  be  produced  con- 
tinually in  a  straight  line ; 

(3)  And  for  every  centre  and  distance  a  circle  can  be 
described ; 

(4-)     And  all  right  angles  are  equal  to  each  other ; 

(5)  And  if  a  straight  line  falling  on  two  straight  lines 
make  the  angles  within  and  towards  the  same  parts  less  than 
two  right  angles,  then  the  two  straight  lines  being  indefinitely 
produced  meet  towards  the  parts  where  are  the  angles  less  than 
two  right  angles. 

(B)     Universal  Ideas : 

(1)  Equals  to  the  same  are  also  equal  to  each  other ; 

(2)  And  if  to  equals  equals  are  added,  the  wholes  are 
equal ; 

(3)  And   if    from    equals    equals    are    subtracted,    the 
remainders  are  equal ; 

(4)  And  things  coinciding  with  each  other  are  equal  to 
each  other; 

(5)  And  the  whole  is  greater  than  the  part. 

How  then  were  these  employed  by  Euclid  to  uphold  his 
view  that  in  space  as  we  know  it  there  is  through  any  given 
point  a  single  duplex  parallel  to  any  given  straight  line  ? — On 
the  one  hand,  he  unconsciously  assumed  the  infinitude  of  space  ; 
or  rather,  he  was  altogether  unconscious  of  the  validity  of  the 
hypothesis  of  the  finite  extent  of  space.  It  is  practically  im- 
possible that  he  should  ever  have  seriously  entertained  the 
idea  that  a  straight  line  is  a  re-entrant  line.  Scarcely  anyone 
had  a  rational  glimpse  of  such  a  possibility  before  Riemann's 
day,  that  is,  before  the  middle  of  the  nineteenth  century. 
Although  the  Third  Postulate  might  be  so  understood  as  to  bar 
out  the  elliptic  hypothesis,  it  was  not  so  devised  (we  must 
think)  by  Euclid  himself.  So  the  Elementist  overlooked  the 
possibility  of  there  being  no  such  thing  at  all  as  parallelism. 

Then  on  the  other  hand  the  possibility  of  double  parallelism 
(hyperbolic  hypothesis)  was  excluded  by  the  Fifth  Postulate, 


Theories  of  Parallelism  3 

which  is  remarkably  distinct  in  character  from  any  other  of  the 
Postulates  and  Axioms.  It  ought  not  to  be  there,  the  student 
feels ;  still  less  ought  it  to  be  among  the  Axioms,  for  surely  its 
occurrence  there  is  one  of  the  most  ludicrous  follies  of  which 
the  human  mind  has  ever  had  to  plead  guilty.  Attempts  at 
remedy  have  continually  occupied  the  attention  of  the  best 
Geometers  of  later  times;  and  their  curious  failure  quite  to 
satisfy  even  themselves  has  hastened  on  the  radical  revision  of 
the  bases  of  Geometry. 

The  Parallel-Postulate  (or  Fifth  Postulate,  as  we  shall  call  it, 
avoiding  the  description  of  it  as  "  Parallel-Axiom ")  was  used 
by  Euclid  in  his  I.  29  in  order  to  prove  the  converse  of  I.  27,  28. 
Let  us  restate  these  Theorems  in  their  simplest  forms,  for 
purposes  of  criticism : 

(i.  27,  28.)  If  two  straight  lines  A  A',  BB'  have  a  common 
perpendicular  MN,  they  never  intersect. 

It  is  noteworthy  that  the  Fifth  Postulate  supplies  what  is 
lacking  here,  in  order  to  make  MA,  NB  satisfy  the  strict 
definition  of  parallelism  given  above  (page  xv),  which  requires 
any  straight  line  near  MA  within  NMA  to  intersect  NB. 
Euclid  did  not  mention  this ;  but  gave  a  proof  by  means  of  his 
I.  16.  Contrast  Ptolemy's  method  below  (page  6).  But  Euc. 
1. 16  is  only  universally  valid  in  space  of  infinite  extent.  If 
space  is  of  finite  extent,  and  the  straight  line  re-entrant  (elliptic 
hypothesis),  let  ABO  be)  a  triangle  so  great  that  if  D  is  the 
middle  point  of  BC,  AD  is  half  the  entire  length  of  a  straight 
line.  Producing  AD  to  A'  such  that  DA'  =  DA,  we  shall  find 
A'  to  be  at  A.  Thus  the  congruence  of  the  triangles  BDA, 
CD  A'  shows  that,  if  Ca  is  the  prolongation  of  AC,  the  angle 
aCB  or  A  CD  is  equal  to  the  angle  DBA  or  CBA.  In  this  case, 
therefore,  the  exterior  angle  of  the  triangle  would  be  equal  to 
an  interior  opposite  angle. 

We  conclude  that  the  enunciation  above  would  constitute  a 
suitable  Postulate  for  excluding  the  elliptic  hypothesis  ;  but  it 
cannot  be  proved  without  assuming  or  postulating  the  infinitude 
of  space.  The  companion  enunciation  now  is  : 

1—2 


4  Theories  of  Parallelism 

(i.  29.)  //  two  straight  lines  AA,  BB'  do  not  intersect,  they 
have  any  number  of  common  perpendiculars  like  MN. 

For  if  N  is  any  point  in  BB',  and  NM  perpendicular  thereto, 
then  also  NM  is  perpendicular  to  AA ';  for,  otherwise,  the 
Parallel-Postulate  would  make  either  MA  intersect  NB  or  else 
MA'  intersect  NB' ,  contrary  to  the  enunciation. 

Evidently,  from  the  form  in  which  they  can  be  enunciated, 
Euc.  I.  27,  28  and  Euc.  I.  29  are  not  completely  converse.  It  is 
significant  also  that  if  one  single  pair  of  straight  lines  were 
allowed  to  possess  one  single  pair  of  common  perpendiculars,  both 
the  elliptic  and  hyperbolic  hypotheses  would  be  cancelled.  In 
such  a  case  the  area/ divergence  constant  would  be  infinite. 
The  plane  would  then  be  of  infinite  size ;  and  through  any 
point  there  would  be  one  duplex  parallel  to  any  straight  line, 
as  by  (ii)  page  xiv. 

In  conclusion,  the  Fifth  Postulate  debars  the  hyperbolic 
hypothesis  in  an  effective  way,  but  it  reads  too  much  like 
a  theorem  and  positively  invites  attempts  at  its  proof. 


POSIDONIUS 

A  lost  work  on  Geometry,  B.C.  80. 

This  Geometer  was  perhaps  one  of  the  earliest  writers  who 
defined  parallels  as  equidistants.  The  assumption  of  the 
rectilinearity  of  equidistants  disposes  at  once  of  the  elliptic  and 
hyperbolic  hypotheses  (see  above,  page  xvii).  "  Posidonius  says 
that  parallel  lines  are  such  as  neither  converge  nor  diverge  in 
one  plane,  but  have  all  the  perpendiculars  drawn  from  points  of 
one  to  the  other  equal.  On  the  other  hand  such  straight  lines 
as  make  their  perpendiculars  continually  greater  or  less  will 
meet  somewhere  or  other,  because  they  converge  towards  each 
other"  (Proclus,  Friedlein's  edition,  page  176).  The  latter 
notion,  only  correct  for  the  parabolic  hypothesis,  was  re-affirmed 
as  self-evident  by  Nasreddin  (below,  page  11). 


Theories  of  Parallelism  5 

GEMINUS 

The  Doctrine  of  Mathematics,  B.C.  70. 

Geminus  was  certainly  a  critic  of  first-rate  ability.  His 
scientific  attitude  is  indicated  in  the  often  quoted  words  of  his, 
recorded  by  Proclus :  "  We  learned  from  the  very  pioneers  of 
the  Science  never  to  allow  our  minds  to  resort  to  weak  plausi- 
bilities for  the  advancement  of  geometrical  reasoning"(Friedlein's 
edition,  page  191).  A  theory  of  parallelism  attributed  to  Aganis 
is  found  not  in  Proclus  but  in  the  Commentary  of  Anaritius 
(Curtze's  edition,  pages  66-73).  So  disappointing  is  this  piece 
of  work  that  it  is  a  relief  to  find  Dr  Heath  maintaining  that 
Aganis  was  almost  certainly  not  Geminus  but  some  writer 
contemporary  with  Simplicius  (A.D.  500).  For  instance,  the 
following  definition  of  equidistant  lines  is  singularly  lacking  in 
precision:  "These  are  such  as  lie  in  one  surface,  and  when 
produced  indefinitely  have  one  space  between  them,  and  it  is  the 
least  line  between  them."  Assuming  Euc.  1. 1-26,  Aganis  would 
prove  that :  "  If  two  straight  lines  are  equidistant,  the  space 
between  them  is  perpendicular  to  each  of  these  lines."  Here 
the  rectilinearity  of  equidistants  is  definitely  but  tacitly  assumed. 
Enunciated  as  a  Postulate,  this  assumption  is  satisfactory, 
except  that  it  assumes  more  than  is  necessary;  more  (for 
instance)  than  the  existence  of  a  rectangle.  Aganis'  proof 
was : 

"  Let  A  A',  BB'  be  two  equidistant  lines,  and  let  MN  be  the 
space  between  them  ;  then  the  line  MN  is  perpendicular  to  each 
of  the  lines  A  A',  BB'.  (Could  a  Greek  mind  think  thus  ?)  For 
if  the  line  MN  were  not  perpendicular  to  each  of  the  two  lines 
A  A',  BB',  the  angles  at  the  point  M  would  not  be  right.  Let 
therefore  one  of  them  AMN  be  an  acute  angle.  Let  me  draw 
then  from  the  point  N  a  perpendicular  Nm  to  the  line  A  A',  and 
let  it  fall  on  the  side  A.  Then  NM  will  be  longer  than  Nm, 
from  the  proof  of  the  tenth  proposition.  But  this  is  to  show  that 
there  is  a  line  less  than  MN  drawn  between  the  lines  AA ,  BB'  \ 
which  is  contradictory  and  impossible.  Therefore  the  line  MN 
is  perpendicular  to  each  of  the  two  lines  A  A ',  BB'." 


6  Theories  of  Parallelism 

The  reference  to  Euc.  I.  10  is  very  ingenious ;  the  construc- 
tion suggests  the  greater  length  of  the  oblique. 


PTOLEMY 

Tractate  on  Fifth  Postulate,  A.D.  150. 

Ptolemy's  interesting  method  of  approaching  the  subject  of 
Parallelism  has  been  preserved  in  summary  by  Proclus  (Fried- 
lein's  edition,  pages  362-367).  He  assumed  Euc.  I.  1-26, 
including  1. 16  which  was  unassailed  until  the  latter  half  of  last 
century.  This  application  of  Euc.  I.  16  to  unlimited  areas 
banishes  the  elliptic  hypothesis  altogether.  Although  not 
perhaps  quite  so  cogent  in  its  original  form,  the  first  of 
Ptolemy's  theorems  to  establish  the  Fifth  Postulate  was 
virtually  as  follows: 

(1)  If  two  straight  lines  AA'  and  BB'  are  crossed  by 
a  transversal  MNso  that  the  interior  angles  AMN,  BNM  on  the 
same  side  of  it  are  together  equal  to  two  right  angles,  then  they 
cannot  ever  intersect. 

For  angles  AMN,  MNB'  are  equal.  And  if  MA  and  NB 
were  to  meet  at  0,  then  by  superposition  of  AMNB  upon 
B'NMA',  MA'  and  NB'  would  be  found  meeting  at  0'  under- 
neath 0.  But  "  two  straight  lines  do  not  enclose  a  space  " ;  and 
therefore  it  is  impossible  that  A  A'  and  BB'  intersect  at  all. 

Of  course,  0  and  0'  may  in  their  actual  positions  be  the 
same  point,  and  indeed  are  so  in  the  (single)  elliptic  hypothesis. 
The  postulate,  not  Euclidean  but  unobjectionable  nevertheless, 
that  two  straight  lines  cannot  intersect  in  two  distinct  points, 
does  not  prevent  the  elliptic  hypothesis  from  being  upheld  and 
maintained.  Methods  being,  if  anything,  more  important  than 
results,  it  may  be  observed  that  the  above  process  by  super- 
position is  a  fine  artifice.  The  letter  H  provides  a  suitable 
figure.  If  the  side-strokes  meet  above,  they  meet  also  below. 
If  these  points  are  somehow  identical,  space  is  singly  elliptic ; 
otherwise,  doubly  elliptic,  an  alternative  only  requiring  mention. 


Theories  of  Parallelism  7 

Reference  may  be  pardoned  to  the  writer's  Story  of  Euclid, 
despite  its  many  faults,  where  a  correct  view-point  (the  greatest 
of  all  difficulties  in  these  matters)  is  aimed  at. 

(2)  Conversely,  if  A  A'  and  BB'  are  parallel,  and  MN  is 
a  transversal,  then  the  angles  AMN,  BNM  are  together  equal 
to  two  right  angles. 

Ptolemy  proved  this  thus :  If  the  angles  AMN,  BNM  are 
not  together  equal  to  two  right  angles,  they  are  either  greater, 
or  else  less.  If  they  are  together  greater  than  two  right  angles, 
so  also  are  the  angles  A'MN,  B'NM,  since  "in  no  wise  are 
MA  and  NB  parallel  more  than  M A  and  NB'."  But  this 
would  be  impossible,  because  the  four  angles  altogether  make 
up  four  right  angles ;  etc. 

This  proof  presupposes  one  and  only  one  parallel  to  BB' 
through  M.  It  assumes  what  has  been  called  the  duplex 
character  of  parallelism,  an  unique  feature  of  the  parabolic 
hypothesis.  This  would  have  been  better  expressed  explicitly 
as  an  alternative  to  the  Fifth  Postulate,  after  the  manner  of 
Proclus  or  Playfair.  For  in  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis,  when 
A  A'  and  BB'  are  parallel  in  the  strict  sense,  A'  A  and  B'B  are 
not  parallel  but  only  asecant  (see  below,  page  43). 

Two  further  theorems  by  Ptolemy  in  this  connexion  are 
given  by  Dr  Heath  in  his  Elements  (pages  205-6,  Vol.  I.)  in 
a  note  upon  the  Fifth  Postulate,  of  which  this  volume  must 
appear  as  an  expansion. 


PROCLUS 

Commentary  on  the  First  Book  of  the  Elements,  A.D.  450. 

The  following  passage  from  Proclus'  Commentary  might 
almost  have  been  written  by  a  nineteenth  century  Geometer 
like  Lobachewski  or  J.  Bolyai. 

"It  cannot  be  asserted  unconditionally  that  straight  lines 
produced  from  less  than  two  right  angles  do  not  meet.  It  is  of 
course  obvious  that  some  straight  lines  produced  from  less  than 


8  Theories  of  Parallelism 

two  right  angles  do  meet,  but  the  (Euclidean)  theory  would 
require  all  such  to  intersect.  But  it  might  be  urged  that  as 
the  defect  from  two  right  angles  increases,  the  straight  lines 
continue  asecant  up  to  a  certain  magnitude  of  the  defect,  and 
for  a  greater  magnitude  than  this  they  intersect." 

Anyone  who  has  been  accustomed  with  M.  Tannery  to 
estimate  Proclus'  work  at  the  level  of  industry  rather  than 
ingenuity  should  certainly  compare  the  following  very  able 
treatment  of  a  difficult  problem  with  any  other  found  in  these 
pages.  In  the  first  place,  Proclus  adduced  (Friedlein's  edition, 
pages  371-373):  Aristotle's  Axiom'.  If  from  any  point  are  drawn 
two  straight  lines  enclosing  an  angle,  then  as  they  are  indefinitely 
produced  the  distance  between  them  exceeds  every  finite  magni- 
tude (De  Caelo,  Bk.  I.).  Although  incapable  of  proof,  this  is 
well  expressed,  and  excellently  fitted  to  form  a  simple  and 
useful  Postulate.  Sharply  and  clearly  it  excludes  the  elliptic 
hypothesis.  If  the  elliptic  hypothesis  must  needs.be  rejected 
at  the  outset,  scarcely  anything  could  be  better. 

In  the  second  place,  how  did  Proclus  evade  the  hyperbolic 
hypothesis  ?  He  laid  down  a  proposition,  again  clear,  sharp, 
and  sufficient.  The  only  objection,  and  it  is  certainly  a  serious 
one,  is  that  he  attempted  a  proof,  and  did  not  (like  his  disciple 
Playfair)  content  himself  with  leaving  it  in  the  region  of 
postulate.  It  was  as  follows: 

Proclus'  Proposition  :  If  a  straight  line  intersect  one  of  two 
parallel  straight  lines,  it  will  also  intersect  the  other. 

"  For  let  A  A'  and  BB'  be  parallels,  and  let  aMaf  cut  A  A'  in 
M.  I  say  that  aMa'  cuts  BB'.  For  if  the  two  straight  lines 
MA,  Ma  are  produced  indefinitely  from  the  point  M,  they 
have  a  distance  greater  than  every  magnitude,  so  that  it 
is  greater  than  the  space  between  the  parallels."  Therefore 
Ma  cuts  BB'. 

If  instead  of  enunciating  this  proposition  in  the  form  of 
a  postulate,  the  proof  is  to  be  made  valid,  some  postulate  must 
be  laid  down  that  the  distance  between  A  A'  and  BB'  remains 
finite.  The  fact  is  doubtless  that  Proclus  shared  that  con- 
ception of  parallelism,  as  a  single  duplex  relationship,  which 


Theories  of  Parallelism  9 

goes  beyond  the  Euclidean  definition.  A  suitable  Postulate 
would  be : 

If  two  straight  lines  have  a  common  perpendicular  of 
finite  length,  the  perpendiculars  from  points  of  one  upon  the 
other  are  all  less  than  some  assignable  magnitude  however 
great. 

This  is  not  the  case  in  hyperbolic  geometry.  We  know 
that  the  length  of  the  perpendicular,  at  finite  distance  even, 
exceeds  every  finite  magnitude,  for  by  page  xvii,  the  length 


K  tanh"1  (cosh  -^ tanh  ^) 
V          -K.  A/ 

6 


\ 
becomes  actually  infinite  for 

x  =  K  cosh"1  ( coth 

This  is  the  very  curious  property  of  the  hyperbolic  plane,  that 
a  quadrilateral  with  three  right  angles  may  have  two  sides 
parallel,  and  the  fourth  vertex  "at  infinity."  Thus  the  con- 
ception of  the  hyperbolic  plane  is  fraught  with  difficulty,  as 
is  more  readily  confessed  for  the  elliptic  plane.  Compare  the 
criticism  of  Dodgson's  figure  below  (page  52). 

Proclus  proved  the  Parallel-Postulate  in  the  following 
manner : 

"Let  A  A'  and  BB'  be  two  straight  lines,  and  let  MN  fall 
across  them  and  make  the  angles  AMN,  BNM  together  less 
than  two  right  angles.... Let  the  angle  aMA  be  made,  equal  to 
this  defect  from  two  right  angles,  and  let  aM  be  produced 
to  a'.  Then  since  MN  falls  across  aa'  and  BB',  and  makes  the 
interior  angles  aMN,  BNM  together  equal  to  two  right  angles, 
the  straight  lines  aa',  BB'  are  parallel.  But  AA'  cuts  aa. 
Therefore  by  the  proposition  above,  AA'  cuts  BB'  also.  There- 
fore AA'  and  BB'  intersect  on  the  side  where  are  the  angles 
together  less  than  two  right  angles." 

An  obiter  dictum  by  Proclus  (Friedlein's  edition,  page  374) 
that  "  Parallelism  is  similarity  of  position,  if  one  may  so  say  " 
illustrates  admirably  the  Euclidean  conception  of  parallelism  ; 
but  the  idea  is  vague,  and  useless  for  scientific  purposes. 


10  Theories  of  Parallelism 

Modern  geometrical  research  has  discarded  all  such  language. 
None  the  less,  non-Euclidean  Geometry  has  been  stigmatised 
as  a  mere  facon  de  parler  (Dr  Karagiannides,  Die  Nicht- 
euklidische  Geometrie  von  Alterthum  zwr  Gegenwart,  1893), 
an  unjust  censure. 


ANAEITIUS 

Commentary  on  the  Elements,  A.D.  900. 

The  Commentary  of  this  Arab  Geometer  was  translated  into 
Latin  by  Gherard  of  Cremona  about  A.D.  1150,  and  this 
translation  has  been  recently  edited  by  Curtze  (Leipzig,  1899). 
It  is  in  this  work  that  Aganis  is  so  often  mentioned  (above, 
page  5).  Apparently  citing  from  the  writings  of  Simplicius 
(A.D.  500),  Anaritius  reports  the  famous  definition  of  a  straight 
line,  made  more  familiar  in  later  days  by  Leibniz  and  Saccheri: 
Linea  recta  est  quaecumque  super  duos  ipsius  extremitates  rotata 
non  movetur  de  loco  suo  ad  alium  locum.  Anarifcius  did  not 
treat  independently  of  the  Parallel-Postulate.  On  page  34 
we  read :  "  On  this  Simplicius  said  :  This  postulate  is  certainly 
not  self-evident,  and  so  it  was  necessary  to  prove  it  by  lines." 


GERBERT 

Mathematical  Works,  A.D.  1000. 

As  would  be  expected  of  one  who  was  not  an  Arab  at  this 
period,  the  works  of  Gerbert  (afterwards  Pope  Sylvester  II) 
contain  no  penetrative  theory  of  parallelism.  In  his  Geometria 
(iv.  10)  he  wrote :  "  Two  straight  lines  distant  from  each  other 
by  the  same  space  continually,  and  never  meeting  each  other 
when  indefinitely  produced,  are  called  parallel,  that  is,  equi- 
distant." Thus  Gerbert  assumed  the  rectilinearity  of  equi- 
distants.  At  this  time  the  results  of  Euclid,  rather  than  his 
methods,  were  studied ;  and  so  were  laid  the  foundations  for 


Theories  of  Parallelism  11 

Savile's  severe  rebuke :  Homines  stulti  et  perridiculi,  quasi  ullus 
unqiiam  artifex  suas  edi  voluerit  conclusiones,  nullis  adjectis 
probationibus. 


NASREDDIN 

Principles  of  Geometry,  A.D.  1250. 

Nasreddin's  attempt  to  prove  the  Parallel- Postulate  was 
explained  by  Wallis  in  a  public  lecture  at  Oxford  on 
February  7th,  1651  (Opera  Mathematica,  Oxford,  1693;  Vol.  n. 
page  669).  The  Persian  Geometer  gave  two  Lemmas,  the 
former  of  which  he  considered  self-evident.  These  were  sub- 
stantially as  follows: 

(1)  If  AA'  and  BB'  are  two  straight  lines,  and  PQ  is  a 
perpendicular  to  BB  terminated  by  AA',  and  if  these  per- 
pendiculars meet  AA'  at  acute  angles  on  the  side  of  A,  B', 
then  the  straight   lines  AA',  BB'  will   approach  each  other 
towards  A,  B  (so  long  as  they  do  not  intersect)  and  recede 
towards  A',  B' ;  and  the  perpendiculars  will  grow  less  on  the 
side  A,  B,  as  far  as  the  intersection  of  AA'  and  BB' ;   and 
greater  on  the  side  A',  B'.     And  conversely. 

"  These  two  propositions  are  self-evident;  and  are  so  familiar 
to  Geometers  both  ancient  and  modern  that  they  are  to  be 
regarded  as  obvious." 

This  is  scarcely  axiomatic  to-day.  It  is  known  that  the 
perpendiculars  may  increase  to  a  maximum  (elliptic  hypothesis), 
or  decrease  to  a  minimum  (hyperbolic  hypothesis),  according 
to  formulae  containing  circular  or  hyperbolic  functions  (see 
above,  page  xvii).  It  is  true  that  the  angles  change  their 
character  in  accordance  with  the  Lemma.  But  the  possibility 
of  a  maximum  or  minimum  perpendicular  intervening  between 
AB  and  A'B'  vitiates  the  proof  of  the  second  Lemma.  If 
this  possibility  were  expressly  negated,  then  the  first  Lemma 
would  make  an  efficient  substitute  for  the  Parallel-Postulate. 

(2)  If  AB,  A'B'  are  equal  perpendiculars  to  BB',  then  the 
angles  at  A  and  A'  are  right. 


12  Theories  of  Parallelism 

For  if  the  angle  A'AB  is  not  right,  suppose  it  (for  instance) 
acute.  Then  by  (1)  AA'  approaches  BB'  towards  A',  B' ;  and 
therefore  A'B  is  of  lesser  length  than  AS,  contrary  to  the 
supposition. 

Having  thus  secured  the  existence  of  a  rectangle,  Nasreddin 
proved  Euc.  I.  32  and  the  Fifth  Postulate.  See  Dr  Heath's 
Elements  (Vol.  I.  page  209). 


BILLINGSLEY 

The  Elements  of  Geometrie,  A.D.  1570. 

Afterwards  Lord  Mayor  of  London,  Sir  Henry  Billingsley 
edited  the  first  printed  edition  of  Euclid's  Elements  in  English. 
He  was  familiar  with  Campanus'  translation  from  Arabic  into 
Latin,  but  his  notes  on  I.  16,  28  were  derived  from  Proclus. 
Under  the  heading :  "  Peticions  or  requestes,"  we  read  : 

"  5.  When  a  right  line  falling  upon  two  right  lines,  doth 
make  on  one  and  the  selfe  same  syde,  the  two  inwarde  angles 
lesse  then  two  right  angles,  then  shal  these  two  right  lines 
beyng  produced  at  length  concurre  on  that  part,  in  which  are 
the  two  angles  lesse  then  two  right  angles. 

...For  the  partes  of  the  lines  towardes  (the  one  side)  are 
more  inclined  the  one  to  the  other,  then  the  partes  of  the  lines 
towardes  (the  other  side)  are...." 

Billingsley  did  not  separate  out  what-is-defined  from  what- 
is-proved  sufficiently.  His  35th  Definition  ran  : 

"  Parallel  or  equidistant  right  lines  are  such ;  which  being 
in  one  and  the  selfe  same  superficies,  and  produced  infinitely  on 
both  sydes,  do  never  in  any  part  concurre." 

But  as  Dr  Henrici  well  says :  "A  good  definition  must 
state  as  many  properties  as  are  sufficient  to  decide  whether 
a  thing  belongs  to  a  class  or  not,  but  not  more  than  are 
necessary  for  this  purpose"  (Congruent  Figures,  London,  1891, 
page  33). 


Theories  of  Parallelism  13 

CLAVIUS 

Euclidis  Elementorum  Libri  xv.,  Rome,  1574. 

Clavius  followed  Proclus  in  revising  the  theory  of  Parallelism, 
and  endeavoured  to  prove  the  Aristotelian  Axiom  that  the 
distance  between  two  intersecting  straight  lines  increases 
beyond  limit.  Thus: 

Let  OMM'  and  ONN'  be  two  intersecting  straight  lines,  and 
let  MN,  M'N'  be  perpendiculars  upon  ONN'.  If  possible,  let 
MN  and  M'N'  be  of  equal  length.  Take  along  N'NO  the 
length  N'Qf  equal  to  NO.  Then  the  triangles  MNO,  M'N'O' 
are  congruent.  Therefore  the  angles  MON,  M'O'N'  are  equal, 
contrary  to  Euc.  I.  16. 

Or  again,  if  possible,  let  MN  exceed  M'N'  in  length,  although 
0,  N,  N'  are  in  this  order.  Take  in  that  case  a  length  N'm' 
along  N'M'  equal  to  NM.  Then  as  before  the  angles  m'O'N' 
and  MON  are  equal.  That  is,  if  m'O'  meets  OMM'  in  m,  the 
angles  mON,  mO'N'  are  equal,  contrary  to  Euc.  I.  16. 

This  is  excellently  arranged ;  but  it  suggests  only  what  is 
already  known,  that  Euc.  I.  16  is  universally  valid  only  in  an 
infinite  space.  Euclid's  16th  proposition  and  Aristotle's  axiom 
contain  the  same  assumption,  the  same  principle,  namely,  that 
the  plane  is  of  infinite  size.  Such  three  statements  are  equiva- 
lent ;  and  any  one  of  them  is  sufficient  to  free  Geometry  from 
the  elliptic  hypothesis. 

Clavius  also  laboured  to  make  evident  from  general  con- 
siderations (which  is  often  an  unprofitable  task  in  Geometry) 
that  equidistants  are  rectilinear.  "  For  if  all  the  points  of  the 
line  AA'  are  equally  distant  from  the  straight  line  BB',  its 
points  will  be  disposed  evenly  (ex  aequo)," — not  crookedly, 
therefore  rectilinearly.  But  the  straight  line  is  not  the  only 
uniform  line.  For  instance,  as  Clavius  himself  remarked,  the 
equidistant  to  a  circle  is  a  circle. 


14  Theories  of  Parallelism 

OLIVER 

De  Rectarum  Linearum  Parallelismo,  Cambridge,  1604. 

Thomas  Oliver,  Physician,  of  Bury,  gave  two  somewhat 
weak  attempts  at  the  proof  of  the  Fifth  Postulate.  These  were 
on  the  following  lines : 

First  Method :  To  prove  that  if  MN  is  a  perpendicular  to 
BB',  and  of  unvarying  length,  then  NM  is  always  perpendicular 
to  "  the  right  line  described  by  the  other  extremity,"  M ;  and  if 
NM  is  always  perpendicular  to  A  A',  then  N  describes  BB'  in 
like  manner. 

For  let  MN,  AB  be  positions  of  the  perpendicular,  then 
MAB  is  to  be  proved  a  right  angle.  Take  Nff  equal  to  NB 
along  BN,  and  let  A'B'  be  the  position  of  the  perpendicular  at 
B'.  Then  the  triangle  ABN  can  be  superposed  upon  the 
triangle  A'B'N,  and  is  congruent  thereto.  Hence  AN,  A  'N  are 
equal;  and  angles  ANM,  A'NM  are  equal.  Hence  the  triangles 
ANM,  A'NM  are  congruent.  And  so  MN  is  perpendicular  to 
AA' — if  (we  must  add)  AMA'  is  one  straight  line. 

Second  Method:  If  AM  and  BN  are  both  perpendicular  to 
MN,  then  any  perpendicular  from  a  point  A  of  A  M  upon  BN 
is  equal  in  length  to  MN,  and  is  perpendicular  to  MA. 

For  let  NM  be  moved  so  as  to  lie  along  BA,  then  shall  M 
fall  upon  A.  Otherwise,  let  NM  assume  the  position  Ba. 
Produce  BN  to  B',  making  NB'  equal  in  length  to  NB ;  and  let 
MN  move  along  NB'  into  the  position  a'B'  perpendicular  to 
NB'  at  B'.  Join  Na,  Na'.  Then  the  triangles  NBa,  NB'a'  are 
superposable,  and  so  congruent.  Hence  the  lengths  Na,  Na' 
are  equal ;  and  the  angles  MNa,  MNa'  are  seen  to  be  equal. 
Thus  the  triangles  MNa,  MNa'  are  superposable,  and  congruent. 
Therefore  the  angles  NMa,  NMa'  are  equal,  and  hence  are  right 
angles ;  so  that  the  angles  AMN,  aMN  are  equal,  which  is 
impossible. 

It  is  assumed  that  aMa'  is  one  straight  line,  which  is 
another  working  of  the  assumption  that  equidistants  are 
rectilinear. 


Theories  of  Parallelism  15 


SAVILE 

Praelectiones  XIII.  in  Principia  Euclidis  Elementorum, 
Oxford,  1621. 

Sir  Henry  Savile  founded  Chairs  of  Geometry  and  Astronomy 
at  Oxford.  He  commended  two  problems  for  consideration  by 
the  professor  of  Geometry.  One  of  these  was  the  Euclidean 
theory  of  parallelism ;  the  other,  the  Euclidean  theory  of  pro- 
portion. He  expressed  his  dissatisfaction  in  epigrammatic 
form:  In  pulcherrimo  Geometriae  corpore  duo  sunt  naevi, 
duae  lobes.  These  "  blots "  were  the  Fifth  Postulate,  and  the 
Fifth  Definition  of  Book  vi.  (the  latter  not  really  Euclid's ;  see 
Dr  Heath's  Elements,  ad  locum).  Savile  died  the  year  after  his 
lectures  were  published  ;  and  a  generation  elapsed  before  John 
Wallis  brought  his  talents  to  bear  upon  the  two  difficulties. 


TACQUET 

Elementa  Geometriae  Planae  et  Solidae,  Amsterdam,  1654. 

The  illustrious  Whiston  stated  in  his  Memoirs  that  "  it  was 
the  accidental  purchase  of  Tacquet's  own  Euclid  at  an  auction 
which  occasioned  his  first  application  to  the  Mathematics, 
wherein  Tacquet  was  a  very  clear  writer." 

Tacquet  defined  parallels  to  be  equidistants,  giving  as  his 
reason  for  so  doing :  Euclidaea  deftnitio  parallelismi  naturam 
non  satis  explicat.  But  he  went  further,  and  inserted  as 
Axioms : 

(11)  Parallel  lines  have  a  common  perpendicular, 

(12)  Two  perpendiculars  cut  off  equal  segments  from  each 
of  two  parallels. 

Concerning  these  he  remarked  that  "  their  truth  is  immedi- 
ately apparent  from  the  definition  of  parallelism."  Nevertheless 
he  condemned  the  Parallel-Postulate,  at  that  time  often  reckoned 
Eleventh  Axiom :  non  axioma  sed  theorema.  His  proof  of  it 


16  Theories  of  Parallelism 

was  neither  very  elegant  nor  very  cogent.  And  still  further,  he 
posited  yet  another  "  axiom,"  that  two  parallels  to  the  same 
straight  line  do  not  intersect.  However  clear  a  writer,  there- 
fore, Tacquet  would  not  be  considered  convincing  by  a  modern 
critic. 


HOBBES 

De  Corpore,  1655 :  et  caetera. 

"There  is  in  Euclid  a  definition  of  strait-lined  parallels ;  but 
I  do  not  find  that  parallels  in  general  are  anywhere  defined ; 
and  therefore  for  an  universal  definition  of  them,  I  say  that  any 
two  lines  whatsoever,  strait  or  crooked,  as  also  any  two  super- 
ficies, are  parallel,  when  two  equal  strait  lines,  wheresoever  they 
fall  upon  them  make  equal  angles  with  each  of  them.  From 
which  definition  it  follows ;  first,  that  any  two  strait  lines, 
not  inclined  opposite  ways,  falling  upon  two  other  strait 
lines,  which  are  parallel,  and  intercepting  equal  parts  in  both  of 
them,  are  themselves  also  equal  and  parallel"  (De  Corpore, 
c.  14,  §  12). 

Hobbes'  definition  of  parallelism  contains  too  much,  when 
applied  to  straight  lines.  A  rectilinear  parallel  to  a  straight 
line  given  should  be  determinate  by  a  single  characteristic  (e.g. 
a  single  act  of  construction,  as  would  be  the  case  if  Euc.  I.  31 
were  made  to  furnish  a  definition).  When  thus  defined,  its 
other  properties  should  be  then  proved.  Otherwise,  something 
has  been  defined  of  which  the  existence  is  not  immediately 
clear.  It  is  wrong  to  assume  two  straight  lines  A  A'  and  BB' 
such  that  if  a  transversal  MN  meet  them  in  M  and  N,  then  if 
M'N'  is  any  other  transversal  equal  to  MN  in  length,  the  angle 
M'N'B'  can  always  be  equal  to  the  angle  MNB'.  The  common- 
sense  philosopher  should  not  veil  such  assumptions  under 
definitions. 

Hobbes  failed  to  disentangle  the  knots  in  the  prevalent 
scheme  of  Geometry.  He  justly  urged  against  Euclid's  defini- 


Theories  of  Parallelism  17 

tion :  "  How  shall  a  man  know  that  there  be  strait  lines 
which  shall  never  meet  though  both  ways  infinitely  produced?" 
(Collected  Works,  Vol.  7,  page  206).  But  the  challenge  applies 
still  more  forcibly  to  his  own  definition  given  above,  which 
Hobbes  had  the  hardihood  to  reproduce  in  this  place  :  "Parallels 
are  those  lines  and  superficies  between  which  every  line  drawn 
in  any  angle  is  equal  to  any  other  line  drawn  in  the  same  angle 
the  same  way."  How  shall  a  man  know  that  there  be  such 
straight  lines  or  plane  surfaces? 


WALLIS 

Demonstratio  Postulati  Quinti  Euclidis,  1663. 

Of  different  character  from  the  preceding  is  the  cautious, 
penetrative  work  of  this  Savilian  Professor,  delivered  as  a  public 
lecture  at  Oxford  on  the  evening  of  July  llth,  1663,  and 
published  in  his  Collected  Works  (Oxford,  1693,  Vol.  2,  pages 
674-678). 

"It  is  known,"  he  began, "  that  some  of  the  ancient  geometers, 
as  well  as  the  modern,  have  censured  Euclid  for  having  postu- 
lated, as  a  concession  required  without  demonstration,  the  Fifth 
Postulate,  or  (as  others  say)  the  Eleventh  Axiom,  or,  with  the 
enumeration  of  Clavius,  the  Thirteenth  Asciom...  But  those  who 
discover  this  fault  in  Euclid  do  themselves  very  often  (at  least, 
as  far  as  I  have  examined  them)  make  other  assumptions  in 
place  of  it,  and  these  appear  to  me  no  easier  to  allow  than  what 
Euclid  postulates...  Since  nevertheless  I  observe  that  so 
many  have  attempted  a  proof,  as  if  they  esteemed  it  necessary, 
I  have  thought  good  to  add  my  own  effort,  and  to  endeavour  to 
bring  forward  a  proof  that  may  be  less  open  to  objection  than 
theirs." 

Wallis  first  laid  down  seven  Lemmas  of  a  simple  and  un- 
exceptionable character  ;  but  the  eighth  contained  something  of 
radical  significance  for  the  Theory  of  Parallelism. 

p.  E.  2 


18  Theories  of  Parallelism 

"VIII.  At  this  stage,  presupposing  a  knowledge  of  the 
nature  of  ratio  and  the  definition  of  similar  figures,  I  assume  as 
an  universal  idea:  To  any  given  figure  whatever,  another  figure, 
similar  and  of  any  size,  is  possible.  Because  continuous 
quantities  are  capable  both  of  illimitable  division  and  illimit- 
able increase,  this  seems  to  result  from  the  very  nature  of 
quantity ;  namely,  that  a  figure  can  be  continuously  diminished 
or  increased  inimitably,  the  form  of  the  figure  being  retained." 

Although  Wallis'  argument  is  insufficient,  this  Principle  of 
Similitude  might  make  a  suitable  substitute  for  Euclid's  Fifth, 
postulate  for  postulate ;  and  moreover  it  has  the  advantage  of 
negating  the  elliptic  hypothesis.  Wallis  however  stated  more 
than  is  really  necessary  for  a  proper  postulate.  If  a  single  pair 
of  triangles  can  be  found  in  a  plane,  of  different  areas  but  of 
equal  angle-sums,  then  the  geometry  of  that  plane  is  Euclidean. 
For  let  A,  A'  be  the  areas,  and  8  the  common  divergence,  then 
as  on  page  xiii  above,  A  =  A  .  8,  A'  =  A  .  S,  where  A  is  a  con- 
stant over  the  plane.  But  A  =}=  A';  and  therefore  S  must  be  zero, 
and  A  infinite ;  and  the  geometry  of  the  plane  is  parabolic. 

Wallis'  proof  of  the  Fifth  Postulate  was  effected  thus :  Let 
MA,  NB  be  two  straight  lines  making  with  MN  the  angles 
AMN,  BNM  together  less  than  two  right  angles.  Suppose  the 
angle  AMN  to  slide  along  MN  until  M  reaches  N.  Then 
because  the  angle  AMN  is  less  than  the  supplement  of  the 
angle  BNM,  AM  in  its  final  position  will  be  outside  BNM. 
Therefore  at  some  position  of  M A  before  M  reaches  N,  say  ma, 
MA  will  intersect  NB,  say  at  p.  Now  by  the  principle  of 
similitude,  it  is  possible  to  draw  on  MN  a  triangle  similar  to 
the  triangle  mNp.  Therefore  corresponding  to  the  point  p 
there  exists  a  point  P  wherein  MA  and  NB  intersect.  Q.E.D. 


Theories  of  Parallelism  19 

LEIBNIZ 

Characteristica  Geometrica,  1679;   In  Euclidis  HPflTA;   etc. 

Leibniz's  geometrical  tracts  have  been  gathered  together  in 
the  first  volume  of  his  collected  mathematical  writings  (Ger- 
hardt's  edition,  Halle,  1858).  Like  his  contemporary  and  rival 
Newton,  Leibniz  was  a  thorough-going  Euclidean  at  heart. 
His  criticisms  are  acute  and  his  suggestions  valuable.  A  plane 
surface  results  when  a  solid  is  cut  in  two  so  that  the  surfaces  of 
section  are  exactly  similar,  even  when  reversed.  A  straight 
line  is  obtained  by  cutting  a  plane  so  that  the  lines  of  division 
are  superposable  in  any  position,  including  the  reversed.  On 
the  Euclidean  definition  of  parallelism  Leibniz  wrote :  "  This 
definition  seems  rather  to  describe  parallels  by  means  of  a  more 
remote  property  than  that  which  they  most  evidently  display ; 
and  one  might  doubt  whether  the  relationship  exists,  or  whether 
all  straight  lines  in  the  plane  do  not  ultimately  intersect  each 
other  "  (page  200).  This  is  a  logical  premonition  of  the  elliptic 
hypothesis.  Leibniz  gave  an  attempt  at  a  demonstration  of  the 
existence  of  rectangles ;  but  the  times  were  not  yet  ripe. 


DA   BITONTO 

Euclide  Restitute,  1680. 

Like  Leibniz,  this  Italian  geometer  would  prefer  a  positive 
definition  of  parallelism.  To  justify  his  own  definition  of 
parallels  as  equidistants,  he  laid  down  fifteen  or  more  proposi- 
tions, analysed  and  discussed  by  Camerer  in  the  edition  of 
Euclid  only  surpassed  by  Dr  Heath's  new  work.  Da  Bitonto's 
fifth  proposition  was :  The  perpendiculars  let  fall  from  points  of 
any  curve  upon  any  straight  line  cannot  all  be  equal.  This 
would  imply  the  rectilinearity  of  equidistants ;  but  the  proof 
does  not  hold  good  for  any  straight  line  whatever. 

2—2 


20  Theories  of  Parallelism 

SACCHERI 

Euclides  ab  omni  naevo  Vindicatus,  Milan,  1733. 

Saccheri's  work  was  forgotten  until  about  twenty  years  ago. 
The  remarks  of  Dr  Stackel  in  this  connexion  are  well  worth 
repeating  at  considerable  length,  from  the  preface  to  that 
scholarly  and  compact  volume  in  which  the  reader  will  find  a 
full  recension  of  the  Jesuit  professor's  apology  for  Euclid 
(Engel  and  Stackel,  Die  Theorie  der  Parallel -linien  von  Euklid 
bis  auf  Gauss^  Leipzig,  1895,  pages  41-136). 

"  Quite  thirty  years  have  elapsed  since  by  the  publication  of 
Riemann's  Inaugural  Dissertation,  and  by  the  appearance  of 
Helmholtz's  Memoir  (on  the  Hypotheses  at  the  basis  of  Geo- 
metry), the  space-problem  and  the  associated  parallel-question 
became  matters  of  general  and  abiding  interest.  About  the 
same  time  it  became  known  that  Gauss  had  realised  long  ago 
the  possibility  and  validity  of  a  geometry  independent  of  the 
Parallel-Axiom,  and  the  rescue  from  oblivion  of  the  writings  of 
Lobachewski  and  J.  Bolyai  was  effected, wherein  this  (hyperbolic) 
geometry  was  systematically  developed.  Gauss,  Lobachewski 
and  J.  Bolyai  were  now  the  putative  originators  of  non- 
Euclidean  Geometry,  of  which  the  further  development  and 
firmer  establishment  were  the  work  of  Riemann  and  Helmholtz. 
Then  a  certain  stir  was  created  in  1889  when  Beltrami  pointed 
out  that  as  early  as  1733  an  Italian  Jesuit,  Gerolamo  Saccheri, 
in  an  attempt  to  prove  Euclid's  Fifth  Postulate,  had  been  led 
to  a  series  of  propositions  hitherto  ascribed  to  Lobachewski  and 
J.  Bolyai....  Then  the  idea  occurred  to  me  whether  possibly 
Saccheri's  Euclides  ab  omni  naevo  Vindicatus  might  not  prove 
to  be  a  link  in  the  chain  of  an  historical  development,  so  that 
the  fundamental  principle  of  continuity  might  perhaps  prevail 
in  the  evolution  of  non-Euclidean  Geometry....  In  the  first 
yearly  issue  (of  the  Magazin  fur  die  reine  und  angewandte 
Mathematik)  a  memoir  on  the  theory  of  parallels  by  Johann 
Heinrich  Lambert  excited  my  attention,  and  a  fuller  examina- 


Theories  of  Parallelism  2i 

tion  led  to  the  startling  conclusion  that  Lambert  must  be  con- 
sidered a  hitherto  disregarded  forerunner  of  Gauss,  Lobachewski 
and  J.  Bolyai." 

Saccheri  protested  against  the  procedure  of  early  Geometers 
who  "assume,  not  without  great  violence  to  strict  logic,  that 
parallel  lines  are  equally  distant  from  each  other,  as  though 
that  were  given  a  priori,  and  then  pass  on  to  the  proofs  of  the 
other  theorems  connected  therewith  "  (page  46). 

It  would  be  a  lengthy  task  to  make  a  detailed  discussion 
of  the  Euclides  Vindicatus.  Saccheri  promises  that  he  will 
apply  Euc.  I.  16,  17  only  to  triangles  limited  in  every  direction, 
yet  has  no  suspicion  about  the  infinitude  of  space.  He  employs 
Euc.  i.  1-15,  18-26  with  entire  freedom.  The  hyperbolic  hypo- 
thesis survives  the  elliptic  for  some  pages.  We  may  sketch 
a  few  of  his  earlier  propositions : 

(1)  If  two  equal  straight  lines  AB,  A'B'  make  equal  angles 
with  any  straight  line  BE  on  the  same  side,  the  angles  of  the 
quadrilateral  at  A  and  A'  are  equal.     This  might  be  proved  by 
superposition ;  but  Saccheri  employs  Euc.  I.  4,  8  mediately. 

(2)  If  the  sides   AA',  BE'  of  such    a   quadrilateral   are 
bisected  in  M,  N,  then  MN  is  perpendicular  to  AA'  and  BB'. 
This  follows  from  (1)  by  Euc.  I.  4,  8.    A  simple  and  direct  proof 
by  superposition  would  suffice. 

(3)  If  two  equal  straight  lines  AB,  A'B'  are  perpendicular 
to  BB',  the  side  A  A'  of  the  quadrilateral  is  equal  to,  or  less  than, 
or  greater  than,  the  opposite  side  BB',  according  as  the  equal 
angles  at  A,  A'  are  right,  or  obtuse,  or  acute,  respectively. 

This  highly  important  General  Theorem  is  proved  in  the 
following  way : 

CASE  I.     When  the  equal  angles  at  A,  A'  are  right. 

For  AA'  is  not  greater  than  BR ;  since  if  it  were  so,  a 
length  A'a  might  be  taken  along  A' A  equal  to  B'B.  Then 
angles  B'Ba,  BaA'  would  be  equal  (Prop.  1).  But  angle  B'Ba 
is  less  than  B'BA  ;  and  angle  BaA'  is  greater  than  BAA' 


22  Theories  of  Parallelism 

(Euc.  I.  16);  so  that  angle  HBa  is  less  than  BaA'.  Nor  is 
AA'  less  than  BB ',  in  like  manner.  And  so  AA'  is  equal 
to  BB'. 

CASE  II.     When  the  equal  angles  at  A,  A'  are  obtuse. 

Bisect  A  A',  BB'  in  M,  N;  then  MN  is  perpendicular  to  both 
A  A'  and  BB'.  Now  AM  is  not  equal  to  BN;  for  if  so,  angles 
MAB,  NBA  would  be  equal ;  and  they  are  not.  Moreover  AM 
is  not  greater  than  BN.  For  if  so,  take  along  MA  a  length  Ma 
equal  to  NB.  Then  angles  MaB,  NBa  are  equal  (Prop.  1). 
But  angle  NBa  is  less  than  a  right  angle ;  and  angle  MaB  is 
greater  than  aAB  (Euc.  I.  16),  which  is  obtuse,  so  that  angle 
MaB  is  decidedly  greater  than  a  right  angle.  [Consideration  of 
the  figure  will  show  that  Euc.  I.  16  is  applicable  even  in  this 
case  of  the  elliptic  hypothesis,  because  the  join  of  B  to  the 
middle  point  of  A  a  is  less  than  BP,  P  being  the  intersection 
of  this  join  with  NM\  and  BP  is  less  than  BO,  0  being  the 
intersection  of  BA  and  NM.  That  is,  BP  is  less  than  half 
the  complete  length  of  a  straight  line  ;  because,  if  BP  were 
equal  to  BO,  angle  BON  would  be  right,  and  B  coincide  with 
B' ;  and  if  BP  were  greater  than  BO,  angle  BON  would  be 
obtuse,  and  BB'  overlap  itself.]  Thus  angle  MaB  exceeds 
NBa.  Therefore  AM  cannot  be  greater  than  BN.  And  A  M  is 
not  equal  to  BN.  Hence  AM  is  less  than  BN. 

CASE  III.     When  the  equal  angles  at  A,  A'  are  acute. 

The  proof  is  similar  to  that  of  Case  II. 

These  three  Cases  Saccheri  termed  the  Hypotheses  of  the 
Right  Angle,  of  the  Obtuse  Angle,  and  of  the  Acute  Angle, 
respectively.  They  were  afterwards  called  the  Parabolic, 
Elliptic,  and  Hyperbolic  Hypotheses  by  Dr  Klein  (see  below, 
page  50). 

(5),  (6),  (7)  If  the  Hypothesis  of  the  Right,  the  Obtuse,  or 
the  Acute  Angle  holds  good  for  one  quadrilateral  of  the  kind 
under  consideration,  it  holds  good  for  every  such  quadrilateral 
throughout  the  entire  plane. 

The  somewhat  lengthy  proofs  make  repeated  use  of  Euc.  I. 
16,  17  (pages  54-58). 


Theories  of  Parallelism  23 

"  (14)  The  Hypothesis  of  the  Obtuse  Angle  is  completely 
false,  because  self-contradictory." 

The  second  of  Saccheri's  proofs  ran  as  follows : 
"  Since  we  have  proved,  with  the  Hypothesis  of  the  Obtuse 
Angle,  that  the  two  acute  angles  of  a  triangle  ABC,  right- 
angled  at  By  are  together  greater  than  a  right  angle,  it  is 
evident  that  an  acute  angle  BAD  can  be  assumed  (on  the  outer 
side  of  BA)  to  make  with  them  two  right  angles.  Then  the 
straight  line  AD,  by  the  foregoing  Proposition  (asserting  the 
Parallel-Postulate)  for  the  Hypothesis  of  the  Obtuse  Angle, 
ultimately  meets  CB.  This  however  clearly  contradicts  Euc.  I. 
17,"  because  if  AD  meets  CB  in  E,  then  the  triangle  EAG  has 
its  angles  at  A  and  C  together  equal  to  two  right  angles. 
Saccheri  failed  to  observe  the  possible  re-entrance  of  straight 
lines  into  themselves,  a  main  feature  of  the  elliptic  hypothesis 
of  space. 

It  may  be  noted  that  Mansion  has  given  the  name  Saccheri's 
Theorem  to  the  proposition  that  in  the  hyperbolic  plane  two 
straight  lines  which  do  not  intersect  have  in  general  a  common 
perpendicular.  The  exceptional  case  is  when  they  are  not 
merely  asecant  but  parallel  (Mathesis,  Vol.  16  Supplt,  1896). 
We  may  also  observe  in  connexion  with  Saccheri's  work  that 
Clairaut  in  1741  enunciated  an  alternative  to  the  Parallel- 
Postulate  in  the  simple  form,  that  a  rectangle  exists. 


SIMSON 
Euclidis  elementorum  libri  priores  sex...  Glasgow,  1756. 

The  famous  Robert  Simson  offered  a  proof  of  the  "  Eleventh 
Axiom  "  by  a  method  involving  a  new  Axiom,  in  the  following 
manner : 

Definition  1.  The  distance  of  a  point  from  a  straight  line  is 
the  perpendicular  from  the  point  upon  the  straight  line. 

Definition  2.  A  straight  line  is  said  to  approach  towards,  or 
recede  from,  another  straight  line  according  as  the  distances  of 


24  Theories  of  Parallelism 

points  of  the  former  from  the  latter  decrease  or  increase.  Two 
straight  lines  are  equidistant,  if  points  of  the  one  preserve  the 
same  distance  from  the  other. 

Axiom :  A  straight  line  cannot  approach  towards,  and  then 
recede  from,  a  straight  line  without  cutting  it;  nor  can  a 
straight  line  approach  towards,  then  be  equidistant  to,  and  then 
recede  from,  a  straight  line  ;  for  a  straight  line  preserves  always 
the  same  direction. 

Simson  appealed  to  common  sense  and  common  experience, 
a  proper  course  for  educational  purposes.  Scientifically,  it 
would  have  been  better  to  postulate  this  property  of  straight 
lines  which  is  peculiar  to  the  parabolic  hypothesis ;  and  also  to 
refrain  from  introducing  the  idea  of  direction  for  support.  The 
suggestion  of  Peletarius  (1557)  that  even  Axioms  themselves  be 
reckoned  as  Definitions  (defining  the  relations  spoken  of  in 
them)  has  been  generally  accepted  to-day  for  scientific  purposes. 
The  tendency  of  the  educationalist  as  such  is  in  the  opposite 
direction,  of  making  as  much  as  possible  present  an  axiomatic 
appearance  to  the  inexperienced  eye  of  the  child. 

Simson's  first  proposition,  proved  by  means  of  his  axiom, 
was: 

If  two  equal  straight  lines  AB,  A'B'  are  perpendicular  to 
any  straight  line  BR,  and  if  from  any  point  M  of  the  join  A  A' 
a  perpendicular  MN  is  let  fall  upon  BB',  then  AB  and  MN  and 
A'B'  are  equal  to  one  another  in  length. 

This  proposition  puts  an  Euclidean  impress  upon  the 
geometry  of  the  plane. 


LAMBERT 

Die  Theorie  der  Parallel-linien,  1766. 

If  two  explorers,  strangers  to  each  other,  enter  an  unknown 
land  beyond  the  mountains  by  the  same  pass,  they  may  quite 
possibly  be  found  to  have  chosen  the  same  route  for  some 
distance  into  the  interior;  and  so  considerable  likeness  exists 


Theories  of  Parallelism  25 

between  the  work  of  Clavius,  Lambert  and  J.  Bolyai  and  the 
earlier  work  of  Nasreddin,  Saccheri  and  Lobachewski.  The 
similarity  between  Saccheri's  treatise  and  Lambert's  memoir  is 
easily  seen  in  the  pages  of  Engel  and  Stackel's  volume.  Lambert 
employed  for  his  fundamental  figure  a  quadrilateral  with  three 
right  angles,  which  is  the  half  of  one  of  Saccheri's  isosceles 
quadrilaterals.  He  stated  expressly  that  the  opposite  sides  of 
his  quadrilateral  did  not  meet,  a  fatal  blow  to  the  elliptic 
hypothesis.  Thus,  for  instance,  in  §  33  he  wrote  (with  reference 
to  a  standard  quadrilateral  A BB' A',  wherein  three  of  the  angles 
at  A,  B  and  E'  are  right  angles),  "the  fact  that  AA'  and  BB' 
do  not  intersect  leaves  it  unsettled  whether  the  distances  AB 
and  A'B'  are  always  equal  or  greater  or  less"  (page  178). 

In  §  39  Lambert  considered  a  figure  in  which  BN,  NB'  are 
equal  distances  along  BB' ;  AB,  MN,  A'B'  perpendiculars  to 
BNB';  and  AM  A'  perpendicular  to  NM  at  M.  He  then 
wrote : 

"  The  question  now  arises  about  the  angle  at  A  ;  and  there- 
fore we  are  bound  to  formulate  three  Hypotheses.  For  it  may 
be  that 

(      equal  to  90°,  (i) 

the  angle  MAB  is  <  or  greater  than  90°,      (ii) 

[  or  less  than  90°.  (iii) 

These  three  Hypotheses  I  will  adopt  in  order,  and  educe  their 
consequences." 

These  are  again  the  parabolic,  elliptic  and  hyperbolic 
hypotheses  of  Dr  Klein.  The  elliptic  hypothesis  (ii)  soon 
dropped  out  of  Lambert's  hands,  owing  to  his  extension  to  the 
entire  (infinite)  plane  of  results  into  which  Euc.  I.  16  enters. 
But  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis  (iii)  was  successfully  worked  out 
to  conclusions  implying  an  absolute  standard  of  length.  On 
this  Lambert  remarked  (§§  80,  81)  : 

"This  consequence  possesses  a  charm  which  makes  one 
desire  that  the  Third  Hypothesis  be  indeed  true  ! 

"  Yet  on  the  whole  I  would  not  wish  it  true,  notwithstand- 
ing this  advantage  (of  an  absolute  standard  of  length),  since 
innumerable  difficulties  would  be  involved  therewith.  Our 


26  Theories  of  Parallelism 

trigonometrical  tables  would  become  immeasurably  vast  (com- 
pare pages  xviii  and  57,  above  and  below) ;  the  similitude  and 
proportionality  of  geometrical  figures  would  wholly  disappear,  so 
that  no  figure  can  be  represented  except  in  its  actual  size; 
astronomy  would  be  harassed  (see  our  Second  Additional 
Note) ;  etc. 

"  Still  these  are  argumenta  ab  amore  et  invidid  ducta,  which 
must  be  banished  from  Geometry  as  from  every  science. 

"I  revert  accordingly  to  the  Third  Hypothesis.  In  this 
hypothesis,  as  already  seen,  not  only  is  the  sum  of  the  three 
angles  of  every  triangle  less  than  180° ;  but  this  difference  from 
180°  increases  directly  with  the  area  of  the  triangle ;  that  is  to 
say,  if  of  two  triangles  one  has  a  greater  area  than  the  other, 
then  in-  the  first  the  sum  of  the  three  angles  is  less  than  in  the 
second." 

Then  in  §  82  Lambert  surmised  that  the  area  of  a  triangle  is 
actually  proportional  to  the  difference  between  its  angle-sum 
and  two  right  angles.  This  has  been  called  Lambert's  Theorem 
by  Mansion  (Mathesis,  Supplt  1896,  Premiers  Prindpes  de  la 
Metageome'trie). 


BERTRAND 

Ddveloppement  Nouveau  de  la  Partie  EUmentaire  des 
MatMmatiques,  Geneva,  1778. 

We  furnish  here  a  few  all  too  brief  extracts  from  the 
elegant  and  perspicuous  disquisitions  of  this  Swiss  Geometer. 

"  Geometry,  like  every  other  science,  has  its  roots  in  ideas 
common  to  all.  From  this  fount  of  ideas  the  first  originators 
derived  those  principles  and  germs  of  knowledge  which  they 
bestowed  upon  mankind.  Hence  it  appears  that  in  every 
science  two  parts  can  be  distinguished  ;  the  first,  consisting  of 
the  assemblage  of  principles  or  primitive  conceptions  from  which 
the  science  proceeds ;  and  a  second,  comprising  the  develop- 
ment of  the  consequences  of  the  principles.  In  respect  of  these 


Theories  of  Parallelism  27 

principles  as  they  exist  in  every  mind,  science  would  seem  to 
encounter  no  resistance  or  difficulty.  Yet  the  choice  that  has 
to  be  made  of  first  principles,  the  degree  of  simplicity  and 
elegance  to  which  they  have  to  be  reduced,  and  the  necessity  of 
enunciating  them  in  precise  terms,  capable  of  clear  compre- 
hension,— all  this  is  very  difficult." 

Bertrand  now  adduced  the  practical  illustration  of  a  Hunter, 
having  shot  a  deer,  measuring  the  length  of  his  shot  in  bow- 
lengths,  and  meditating  upon  the  sense  of  direction  exercised 
when  he  aimed  the  fatal  arrow.  He  then  proceeded  with  much 
eloquence  :  "  The  spectacle  of  the  universe  displays  before  our 
eyes  an  immense  space.  In  this  immensity  bodies  exist  and 
change  continually  their  shape,  size  and  position ;  and  mean- 
while space  itself,  invariable  in  all  its  parts,  remains  like  a  sea 
always  calm,  in  everlasting  repose.  So  the  idea  we  form  of 
space  is  that  it  is  infinite  and  limitless ;  homogeneous  and  like 
itself  at  every  time  and  in  every  place.  Space  is  without 
bounds,  for  any  we  might  assign  to  it  would  be  contained  in  it, 
and  therefore  would  not  bound  it.  Space  is  homogeneous,  in 
that  the  portion  of  space  occupied  by  a  body  in  one  plane 
would  not  differ  from  that  which  would  be  occupied  by  it 
elsewhere." 

Division  of  space  into  two  halves  identical  in  all  but  position 
gives  the  plane  surface;  and  division  of  the  plane  similarly 
gives  the  straight  line  (so  also  Leibniz,  above,  page  19). 

So  far,  so  good.  But  the  elliptic  hypothesis  escapes  from 
the  Hunter's  grasp  in  his  seventh  effort  of  thought,  as  from 
Ptolemy's  many  centuries  before. 

"  Proposition  7.  Two  straight  lines  AM A',  BMB'  traced  on 
the  same  plane,  and  making  with  a  third  MN  the  interior 
angles  AMN,  BNM  of  which  the  sum  is  equal  to  two  right 
angles,  cannot  intersect." 

For  AMNB  can  be  superposed  upon  BNM  A'.  "  Hence  it 
will  follow  that  the  straight  Hues  A  A',  BB'  will  intersect  in  two 
points,  or  will  not  intersect  at  all.  But  the  first  is  impossible, 
therefore  the  second  is  true." 


28  Theories  of  Parallelism 

This  is  incisive;  but  as  remarked  above  (page  6)  these 
presumably  very  distant  points  may  be  one  and  the  same  point. 

The  Hunter's  thoughts  are  supposed  to  turn  next  to  an 
eighth  Proposition,  equivalent  to  the  following  :  The  plane  con- 
tains an  infinite  number  of  strips  such  as  are  formed  by  two 
perpendiculars  MA,  NB  to  a  limited  straight  line  MN  on  the 
same  side  of  it.  For  if  MN  is  produced  to  P,  and  NP  is  equal 
to  MN,  and  PC  drawn  perpendicular  to  NP,  then  the  strip 
AMNB  can  be  superposed  upon  the  strip  BNPG.  And  space 
being  infinite  by  the  preceding  Proposition,  this  process, 
repeated  infinitely  often,  furnishes  an  infinite  number  of  strips, 
congruent  to  AMNB,  over  half  of  the  infinite  plane. 

Then  the  Hunter  elaborates  one  of  the  finest  proofs  of  the 
Parallel-Postulate  of  which  we  have  knowledge,  after  this 
manner  : 

Let  MH  be  drawn  within  the  strip  AMNB  ;  then  MH 
meets  NB.  For  the  area  included  within  the  angle  AMH  is 
a  finite  fraction  of  the  area  of  the  entire  plane  ;  in  fact,  the 
same  fraction  that  the  angle  AMH  is  for  a  denominator  of  four 
right  angles.  Whereas  the  area  of  the  strip  AMNB  has  been 
seen  to  be  only  an  infinitesimal  fraction  of  the  whole  plane  ;  in 
fact,  the  same  fraction  that  the  length  MN  is  for  an  infinite 
denominator  (the  whole  length  of  a  straight  line).  Hence  the 
angle  AMH  cannot  be  contained  within  the  strip  AMNB. 
Therefore  it  must  overlap.  Therefore  MH  must  intersect  and 
cross  NB. 

This  is  exceedingly  forcible,  indeed  almost  overwhelming. 
It  seems  to  pierce  the  heart  of  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis,  like 
a  swift  arrow  from  a  sure  bow.  Let  us  see  whether  any  light  is 
shed  upon  it  by  our  results  for  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis 
on  page  xvii  above.  The  area  of  the  angle  AMH  is  a  certain 
definite  fraction  of  the  area  of  the  infinite  plane.  Take  then 
a  circle  of  any  assigned  radius  R  however  large,  its  centre 
being  M.  The  area  of  this  circle  is 


!R  sinh  ^  dx  =  ZirK*  (  cosh  §  -  1  V 
Jo  A  \         K        / 


Theories  of  Parallelism  29 

When  R  becomes  indefinitely  great,  even  compared  with  the 
space-constant  K,  the  value  of  this  expression  is  of  the  order  of 

R 

magnitude  trK^eK.     Thus  if  the  angle  AMH  is  ft  in  circular 
measure,  the  area  of  the  sector  AMH  is  not  very  different  from 


Now  let  us  consider  the  area  of  the  strip  AMNB,  and  write 
b  for  the  length  MN,  then  by  considering  a  very  great  number 
of  very  narrow  strips  all  of  length  R,  we  have  for  the  area 
required 

R 

K' 

b      2 

which  is  not  very  different  from  ^  KeK,  the  further  boundary  of 


/R          x 
cosh  ^.dx  =  bK  sinh 
)          -ft 


the  strip  being  an  equidistant  on  MN  of  height  R. 

Thus  the  ratio  of  the  areas  of  sector  and  strip,  computed 
thus,  is  practically  j-  Ky  which  is  always  finite ;  and  indeed  may 

be  made  as  small  as  desired  by  choosing  the  angle  ft  small 
enough. 

There  may  be  observed  an  inconsistency  in  the  areas  of  the 
hyperbolic  plane  computed  by  means  of  an  infinite  number  of 

sectors  and  an  infinite  number  of  strips.     A  circle  of  very  great 

R 
radius  R  has  area  7rK2eK  approximately.     But  a  double  strip  of 

R 

length  2R  has  an  area  of  about  bKeK.  And  as  the  number  of 
strips  is  certainly  infinite,  the  area  of  the  plane  reckoned  in 
strips  infinitely  exceeds  the  area  of  the  plane  reckoned  in 
sectors.  The  reason  is  this.  The  space  between  a  circle  of 
great  diameter  2R  and  the  equilateral  circumscribing  quad- 
rilateral of  medial  dimensions  2R,  is  ultimately  infinite  com- 
pared with  the  area  of  the  circle,  in  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis. 
There  is  a  like  point  to  be  raised  in  criticism  of  Dodgson's 
figure  (below,  page  52). 


30  Theories  of  Parallelism 

None  the  less,  the  above  piece  of  rigorous  analysis  is  very 
different  from  that  simple,  convincing  objection  which  one 
would  wish  to  raise.  The  only  possible  elementary  criticism 
appears  to  be  that  more  is  assumed  about  the  infinite  regions  of 
the  plane  than  we  can  really  know  or  conceive.  Probably  the 
experts  will  consider  the  argument,  on  this  or  other  grounds, 
one  of  the  most  plausible  and  fallacious  of  sophisms. 

For  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis,  the  rectangular  strip  widens 
out  ultimately  at  the  same  rate  as  a  circular  sector;  and  our 
mental  picture  of  such  infinitely  distant  regions  is  not  legitimate 
unless  drawing  to  scale  (Wallis'  principle)  is  a  legitimate  and 
indeed  possible  procedure.  If  there  is  no  court  of  appeal  from 
the  verdict  of  "commonsense,"  Bertrand's  argument  stands,  and 
Euclid's  geometry  prevails. 


PLAYFAIR 

Elements  of  Geometry,  Edinburgh,  1795. 

John  Pluyfair  was  a  typical  expositor  of  Euclidean  Geometry. 
What  has  become  generally  known  as  Playfair's  Axiom  is  only 
a  slightly  varied  form  of  Proclus'  Proposition  (above,  page  8). 
Playfair  wrote : 

"A  new  Axiom  is  introduced  in  the  room  of  the  12th,  for 
the  purpose  of  demonstrating  more  easily  some  of  the  properties 
of  parallel  lines." 

This  new  Axiom,  assigned  the  llth  place,  was  couched  in 
the  familiar  terms : 

"  Two  straight  lines  which  intersect  one  another,  cannot  be 
both  parallel  to  the  same  straight  line." 

As  will  be  seen  by  a  comparison  with  Lobachewski's  position 
(below,  page  43),  this  prevents  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis ;  and 
the  elliptic  hypothesis  would  probably  have  been  thought  by 
Playfair  to  be  sufficiently  frustrated  by  the  corollary  to  his 
definition  of  the  straight  line,  that  two  straight  lines  cannot 
enclose  a  space. 


Theories  of  Parallelism  31 

Of  this  Axiom  of  Playfair's,  Cayley  said  :  "  My  own  view  is 
that  Euclid's  Twelfth  Axiom  in  Playfair's  form  of  it,  does  not 
need  demonstration,  but  is  part  of  our  notion  of  space,  of  the 
physical  space  of  our  experience,  which  is  the  representation 
lying  at  the  bottom  of  all  external  experience"  (Presidential 
Address  to  the  British  Association,  1883).  Dr  Russell  cites  and 
criticises  this  interesting  confession  in  his  admirable  Foundations 
of  Geometry  (Cambridge,  1899,  page  41). 


LAPLACE 

Exposition  du  Systeme  du  Monde,  Paris,  1796. 

This  great  Analyst  expressed  his  views  to  a  certain  extent, 
in  connexion  with  the  Law  of  Universal  Gravitation  (Harte's 
translation,  Dublin,  1830,  page  321). 

"The  law  of  attraction,  inversely  as  the  square  of  the 
distance,  is  that  of  emanations  which  proceed  from  a  centre... 
One  of  its  remarkable  properties  is,  that  if  the  dimensions  of  all 
the  bodies  in  the  universe,  their  mutual  distances  and  velocities, 
increase  or  diminish  proportionally,  they  describe  curves  entirely 
similar  to  those  which  they  at  present  describe ;  so  that  if  the 
universe  be  successively  reduced  to  the  smallest  imaginable 
space,  it  will  always  present  the  same  appearance  to  all 
observers...  The  simplicity  of  the  laws  of  nature  therefore  only 
permits  us  to  observe  the  relative  dimensions  of  space." 

On  the  other  hand,  Gauss  (below,  page  34)  remarked  the 
possibility  of  objects  possessing  absolute  dimensions;  and  the 
analysis  of  celestial  mechanics  becomes  much  more  intricate  if 
the  law  of  the  inverse  square  has  to  be  abandoned  or  assigned 
a  subordinate  place.  For  the  elliptic  and  hyperbolic  hypotheses, 
the  area  of  a  sphere  of  radius  r  is 

4^sin3T    and    4flT2sinh24? 
k  K 

respectively.     Thus  the  law  of  intensity  of  radiation  issuing 


32  Theories  of  Parallelism 

uniformly  from  a  point-source  would  for  the  three  hypotheses  be 
expressed  by  the  factors 

T  T 

cosec2  y- ,     r"2,     cosech2  -^ . 
K  K 

The  application  of  these  extended  laws  to  planetary  motion 
is  the  task  undertaken  in  the  Second  Additional  Note  to  this 
volume  (page  62). 

The  translator's  note  (page  536)  may  be  reproduced  here : 
"The  endeavours  of  Geometers  to  demonstrate  Euclid's 
Twelfth  Axiom  about  parallel  lines  have  been  hitherto  un- 
successful. However  no  person  questions  the  truth  of  this 
Axiom,  or  of  the  Theorems  which  Euclid  has  deduced  from  it. 
The  perception  of  extension  contains  therefore  a  peculiar 
property  which  is  self-evident,  without  which  we  could  not 
rigorously  establish  the  doctrine  of  parallels.  The  notion  of 
a  limited  extension  (for  example,  of  a  circle)  does  not  involve 
anything  that  depends  on  its  absolute  magnitude ;  but  if  we 
conceive  its  radius  to  be  diminished,  we  are  forced  to  diminish 
in  the  same  proportion  its  circumference,  and  the  sides  of  all 
the  inscribed  figures.  This  proportionality  was,  according  to 
Laplace,  much  more  obvious  than  that  of  Euclid.  It  is  curious 
to  observe  that  agreeably  to  what  is  stated  on  page  322,  this 
Axiom  is  pointed  out  in  the  results  of  universal  gravitation." 

Certainly  the  utterances  of  great  minds  are  always  deserving 
of  careful  attention,  and  repay  it. 


GAUSS 

Letters  and  Reviews,  1799-1846. 

For  nearly  fifty  years  the  mind  of  Gauss  was  repeatedly 
engaged  upon  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis,  styled  by  him  non- 
Euclidean  Geometry.  His  occasional  writings,  collected  by 
Engel  and  Stackel,  are  humanly  interesting.  His  influence  was 
exerted  upon  the  elder  Bolyai,  and  so  indirectly  upon  the 
brilliant  son,  Johann  Bolyai.  In  a  letter  to  the  father  towards 
the  close  of  the  year  1799,  Gauss  wrote : 


Theories  of  Parallelism  33 

"  I  have  arrived  at  much  which  most  people  would  regard  as 
proved,  but  it  is  in  my  eyes  good  for  nothing  in  this  respect. 
For  example,  if  it  could  be  proved  that  a  rectilinear  triangle  is 
possible,  of  area  exceeding  any  assigned  area,  I  should  be  in 
a  position  to  prove  rigorously  the  whole  of  (Euclidean)  geometiy. 
Now  most  people  would  regard  this  as  axiomatic,  but  I  do  not. 
It  would  be  quite  possible  that  however  distant  from  each 
other  the  vertices  of  the  triangle  were  assumed  to  lie  in  space, 
the  area  should  still  be  less  than  an  assignable  limit.  I  have 
more  propositions  of  a  similar  character,  but  in  none  of  them  do 
I  find  anything  really  satisfying." 

In  fact,  the  maximum  area  of  a  triangle  formed  by  three 
straight  lines  for  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis  would  be 

K*(ir-A-B-C)t 

wherein  A=B  =  C=Q,  that  is,  TrK2,  which  though  probably 
large  is  strictly  limited.  The  sides  of  the  triangle  would  be 
parallel  in  pairs,  and  the  vertices  "  at  infinity." 

Thus  Gauss  seems  to  have  worked  out  several  fundamental 
theorems  of  hyperbolic  geometry  but  not  so  completely  as  to 
feel  ready  to  publish  them.  His  letter  to  Taurinus,  a  facsimile 
of  which  forms  the  frontispiece  to  Parallel-linien  von  Euklid  bis 
auf  Gauss,  reads  as  follows : 

"  I  have  read  not  without  pleasure  your  kind  letter  of  October 
30th  with  the  small  sketch  enclosed,  the  more  so  because  I 
have  been  accustomed  to  discover  scarcely  any  trace  of  pure 
geometrical  spirit  among  the  majority  of  people  who  make  the 
new  attempts  on  the  so-called  Theory  of  Parallel  Lines.  With 
reference  to  your  attempt  I  have  nothing,  or  not  much,  to 
observe  except  that  it  is  incomplete.  Your  presentation  of  the 
proof  that  the  sum  of  the  three  angles  of  a  plane  triangle 
cannot  be  greater  than  180°  leaves  much  to  be  desired  in 
respect  of  geometrical  rigour.  This  in  itself  could  be  remedied, 
and  beyond  all  doubt  the  impossibility  can  be  proved  most 
rigorously.  Things  stand  otherwise  in  the  second  part,  that  the 
sum  of  the  angles  cannot  be  less  than  180° ;  this  is  the  crucial 

F.  E.  3 


34  Theories  of  Parallelism 

point,  the  reef  on  which  all  the  wrecks  take  place.  I  imagine 
that  you  have  not  been  long  occupied  with  this  subject.  My 
own  interest  in  it  has  extended  over  30  years,  and  I  do  not 
think  that  anyone  can  have  occupied  himself  more  with  this 
second  part  than  I,  although  I  have  never  published  anything 
on  it.  The  assumption  that  the  sum  of  the  three  angles  of 
a  triangle  is  less  than  180°  leads  to  a  peculiar  Geometry  entirely 
different  from  ours, — a  geometry  completely  self-consistent, 
which  I  have  developed  for  myself  perfectly  satisfactorily,  so 
that  I  can  solve  any  problem  in  it  with  the  assumption  that  a 
constant  is  determinate,  this  constant  not  being  capable  of 
a  priori  specification.  The  greater  this  constant  is  assumed  to 
be,  the  more  nearly  is  Euclidean  Geometry  approached ;  and  an 
infinite  value  of  the  constant  makes  the  two  systems  coincide. 
The  theorems  of  this  geometry  seem  somewhat  paradoxical,  and 
to  the  lay  mind  absurd ;  but  continued  steady  reflexion  shows 
them  to  contain  nothing  at  all  impossible.  Thus,  for  instance, 
the  three  angles  of  a  triangle  can  be  as  small  as  we  please,  if 
only  the  sides  are  taken  sufficiently  great ;  and  yet  the  area  of 
a  triangle  can  never  exceed  a  definite  limit,  however  great  the 
sides  are  taken  to  be,  and  indeed  can  never  reach  it.  All  my 
efforts  to  discover  a  contradiction,  an  inconsistency,  in  this  non- 
Euclidean  Geometry  have  been  unsuccessful ;  and  the  one  thing 
in  it  contrary  to  our  conceptions  is  that,  were  the  system  true, 
there  must  exist  in  space  a  linear  magnitude,  determined  for 
itself  albeit  unknown  to  us.  But  methinks,  despite  the  say- 
nothing  word-wisdom  of  the  metaphysicians,  we  know  far  too 
little,  too  nearly  nothing,  about  the  true  nature  of  space,  for 
us  to  confuse  what  has  an  unnatural  appearance  with  what  is 
absolutely  impossible.  If  the  non-Euclidean  Geometry  were 
true,  and  that  constant  at  all  comparable  with  such  magnitudes 
as  lie  within  reach  of  our  measurements  on  the  earth  or  in 
the  heavens,  it  could  be  determined  a  posteriori.  Hence  I  have 
sometimes  expressed  in  jest  the  wish  that  the  Euclidean 
Geometry  were  not  true,  since  then  we  should  possess  an 
absolute  standard  of  measurement  a  priori.  I  am  not  afraid 
that  a  man  who  has  shown  himself  to  possess  a  thoughtful 
mathematical  mind  will  misunderstand  the  foregoing;  but  in  any 


Theories  of  Parallelism  35 

case,  please  regard  this  as  a  private  communication,  of  which 
public  use,  or  use  leading  to  publicity,  is  not  to  be  made  in  any 
way.  If  at  some  future  time  I  acquire  more  leisure  than 
in  my  present  circumstances,  I  shall  perhaps  publish  my 
investigations. 

Gottingen,  November  8th,  1824" 

These  investigations  continued  in  the  condition  of  scattered 
epistolary  hints  and  suggestions  until  the  decease  of  the  fore- 
most mathematician  of  his  day.  The  solution  of  any  problem, 
referred  to  by  Gauss  as  possible  for  him,  is  also,  at  least  in 
principle,  possible  by  the  use  of  the  analytical  formulae 
obtained  in  the  First  Additional  Note  at  the  end  of  this 
volume  (page  59). 


CAENOT 

Geometric  de  Position,  Paris,  1803. 

Carnot  advocated  the  Principle  of  Similitude  as  an  alter- 
native to  the  Parallel-Postulate,  a  view-point  secured  with 
greater  elaboration  by  Wallis  (above,  page  18).  He  wrote 
(§  435): 

"The  Theory  of  Parallels  rests  on  a  primitive  idea  which 
seems  to  me  almost  of  the  same  degree  of  clearness  as  that 
of  perfect  equality  or  of  superposition.  This  is  the  idea  of 
Similitude.  It  seems  to  me  that  we  may  regard  as  a  principle 
of  the  first  rank  that  what  exists  on  a  large  scale,  as  a  ball, 
a  house,  or  a  picture,  can  be  reduced  in  size,  and  vice  versa-, 
and  that  consequently,  for  any  figure  we  please  to  consider,  it  is 
possible  to  imagine  others  of  all  sizes  similar  to  it;  that  is  to 
say,  such  that  all  their  dimensions  continue  to  be  in  the  same 
proportions.  This  idea  once  admitted,  it  is  easy  to  establish  the 
Theory  of  Parallels  without  resorting  to  the  idea  of  infinity." 


3—2 


36  Theories  of  Parallelism 


W.   BOLYAI 

Theoria  Parallelarum,  Maros-Vasarheli,  1804- ; 
Kurzer  Grundriss,  1851. 

In  the  earlier  of  these  tracts,  reprinted  in  the  49th  volume 
of  Mathematische  Annalen  (pages  168-204),  the  elder  Bolyai 
begau  by  supposing  an  inverted  T-square  to  slide  along  a 
straight  line.  What  is  the  curve  described  by  the  upper  end 
of  it  ? 

The  discussion  of  this  equidistant  line  in  a  rather  awkward 
manner  led  the  Hungarian  Geometer  to  a  conviction  of  the 
validity  of  Euclidean  Geometry. 

In  the  second  tract  was  introduced  an  ingenious  substitute 
for  the  Parallel-Postulate : 

Let  it  be  conceded  that  "  if  three  points  are  not  in  a 
straight  line,  then  they  lie  on  a  sphere " :  and  therefore  on 
a  circle. 

To  prove  from  this  the  principle  of  the  Parallel-Postulate, 
let  A,  B,  A'  be  the  three  points.  Let  M,  M'  be  the  middle 
points  of  AB,  BA' ;  and  MN,  M'N'  drawn  perpendicular  to 
them.  Then  the  sum  of  the  angles  M'MN,  MM'N'  is  less  than 
two  right  angles  by  the  sum  of  the  angles  BMM',  BM'M. 
Now  MN  and  M'N'  must  meet,  in  the  centre  of  the  circle 
(or  sphere),  unless  ABA'  is  straight.  That  is,  however  close 
the  sum  of  the  angles  M'MN,  MM'N'  is  to  two  right  angles, 
MN  and  M'N'  intersect.  Q.E.D. 

The  elder  Bolyai  did  not  entertain  the  possibility  of  MN, 
M'N'  continuing  to  intersect  when  ABA'  is  one  straight  line; 
nor  did  his  brilliant  son  work  out  the  elliptic  hypothesis.  Like 
Lobachewski,  the  younger  Bolyai  only  elaborated  a  hyperbolic 
geometry.  They  both  however  discussed  the  properties  of 
curves  (Z-lines,  horocycles)  neither  rectilinear  nor  circular, 
whereof  the  normals  are  parallel.  Only  in  Euclidean  Geometry 
is  the  straight  line  the  limit  of  a  circle  of  indefinitely  increased 
radius. 


Theories  of  Parallelism  37 

THIBAUT 

Grundriss  der  reinen  Matheniatik,  Gottingen,  1809. 

Any  treatment  of  parallelism  based  upon  the  idea  of  direc- 
tion assumes  that  translation  and  rotation  are  independent 
operations,  and  this  is  only  so  in  Euclidean  Geometry.  The 
following  is  the  easiest  and  most  plausible  way  of  establishing 
the  parabolic  hypothesis.  From  Euc.  I.  32  can  be  deduced  very 
readily  the  Euclidean  theory  of  parallelism.  Thibaut  argued 
for  this  theorem  as  follows : 

"Let  ABC  be  any  triangle  whose  sides  are  traversed  in 
order  from  A  along  AB,  BC,  CA.  While  going  from  A  to  B 
we  always  gaze  in  the  direction  ABb  (AB  being  produced  to  6), 
but  do  not  turn  round.  On  arriving  at  B  we  turn  from  the 
direction  Bb  by  a  rotation  through  the  angle  bBG,  until  we 
gaze  in  the  direction  BCc,  Then  we  proceed  in  the  direction 
BCc  as  far  as  C,  where  again  we  turn  from  Cc  to  CAa  through 
the  angle  cCA  ;  and  at  last  arriving  at  A,  we  turn  from  the 
direction  Aa  to  the  first  direction  AB  through  the  external 
angle  aAB.  This  done,  we  have  made  a  complete  revolution, — 
just  as  if,  standing  at  some  point,  we  had  turned  completely 
round ;  and  the  measure  of  this  rotation  is  2?r.  Hence  the 
external  angles  of  the  triangle  add  up  to  2?r,  and  the  internal 
angles  A  +  B  4-  C  =  TT.  Q.E.D." 

TAURINUS 

Theorie  der  Parallel-linien,  1825. 

Taurinus  expressed  eight  objections  to  the  wider  range 
of  Geometry  then  being  manifested  (Engel  and  Stackel,  pages 
208-9). 

"1.  It  contradicts  all  intuition.  It  is  true  that  such  a 
system  would  in  small  figures  present  the  same  appearance 
as  the  Euclidean ;  but  if  the  conception  of  space  is  to  be 
regarded  as  the  pure  form  of  what  is  indicated  by  the  senses, 
then  the  Euclidean  system  is  incontestably  the  true  one,  and  it 


38  Theories  of  Parallelism 

cannot  be  assumed  that  a  limited  experience  could  give  rise  to 
actual  illusion." 

None  the  less,  however,  measurement  of  angles,  if  sufficiently 
exact,  might  deal  a  fatal  blow  to  Euclid's  a  priori  system,  by 
subverting  Euc.  I.  32. 

"  2.  The  Euclidean  system  is  the  limit  of  the  first  system, 
wherein  the  angles  of  a  triangle  are  more  than  two  right  angles. 
With  this  procedure  to  the  limit,  the  paradox  in  connexion  with 
the  axiom  of  the  straight  line  ceases." 

In  fact  Taurinus  did  not  overcome  the  difficulty  universally 
experienced  in  respect  of  the  elliptic  hypothesis.  Further  on 
he  wrote  (Engel  and  Stackel,  page  257): 

"In  this  theorem  (51)  it  is  proved  that  with  the  assumption 
that  the  angle-sum  of  a  quadrilateral  can  be  greater  than  four 
right  angles  (or,  what  comes  to  the  same  thing,  if  the  angle- 
sum  of  a  triangle  can  be  greater  than  two  right  angles),  then 
all  the  lines,  perpendicular  to  another  line,  intersect  in  two  points 
at  equal  distance  on  either  side.  Hence  arises  the  evident 
contradiction  of  the  axiom  of  the  straight  line,  and  so  such  a 
geometrical  system  cannot  be  rectilinear." 

To  continue : 

"  3.  Were  the  third  system  the  true  one,  there  would  be 
no  Euclidean  Geometry,  whereas  however  the  possibility  of  the 
latter  cannot  be  denied." 

Certainly  the  possibility  of  the  Euclidean  system  cannot  be 
denied,  but  its  actuality  may  be  doubted.  It  is  so  infinitely 
special  an  hypothesis.  By  way  of  analogy,  does  a  single  comet 
in  the  universe  possess  a  strictly  parabolic  orbit  ? 

"4.  In  the  assumption  of  such  a  system  as  rectilinear, 
there  is  no  continuous  transition ;  the  angles  of  a  triangle  could 
only  make  more  or  less  than  two  right  angles." 

The  Euclidean  system,  nevertheless,  is  the  connecting  link 
desired  between  the  elliptic  and  hyperbolic  geometries.  It  is 
the  limit  of  each ;  whether  it  separates  them  or  unites  them  is 
only  a  matter  of  words. 

"  5.  These  systems  would  have  quite  paradoxical  conse- 
quences, contradicting  all  our  conceptions ;  we  should  have  to 
assign  to  space  properties  it  cannot  have." 


Theories  of  Parallelism  39 

This  appeal  to  commonsense  is  of  value  in  practical  work, 
where  close  approximation  suffices. 

"  6.  All  complete  similarity  of  surfaces  and  bodies  would 
be  wanting;  and  still  this  idea  seems  to  have  its  roots  in 
intuition,  and  to  be  a  true  postulate." 

The  view  of  some  of  the  world's  greatest  thinkers, — and 
they  have  Wallis  for  spokesman. 

"  7.  The  Euclidean  system  is  in  any  case  the  most  complete, 
and  its  truth  therefore  possesses  the  greatest  plausibility." 

But  all  three  hypotheses  together  supply  a  more  complete 
Theory  of  Space  than  any  single  one  of  them,  and  their  common 
basis  is  the  assumption  that  space  is  homogeneous.  More 
complete  still  will  be  the  Geometry  of  the  future,  contem- 
plating a  heterogeneous  space  (compare  Clifford's  speculation ; 
below,  page  49). 

"  8.  The  internal  consistency  of  the  third  system  is  no 
reason  for  regarding  it  as  a  rectilinear  system ;  however,  there 
is  in  it,  so  far  as  we  know,  no  contradiction  of  the  axiom  of  the 
straight  line  as  in  the  first." 

These  objections  are  mainly  of  an  a  priori  character.  On 
the  other  hand,  our  knowledge  of  space  as  an  objectivity  is 
small.  Increased  precision  of  astronomical  instruments  might 
display  antipodal  images  of  a  few  bright  stars,  and  this  would 
then  tell  in  favour  of  an  elliptic  hypothesis.  The  space-constant 
is  large,  very  large;  but  no  experiment  can  ever  prove  it  infinite, 
as  Euclideans  assume  it. 


J.   BOLYAI 

Appendix  scientiam  spatii  e#/w'&ews...Maros-Vasarheli,  1832. 

English,  German  and  French  translations  have  been  made 
of  this  brilliant  tractate  by  Halsted,  Frischauf  and  Hoiiel,  the 
first  under  the  title  Science  Absolute  of  Space  (Austin,  Texas, 
1896).  Bolyai  gave  independently  therein  a  clear,  brief,  and 
sound  introduction  to  the  study  of  the  hyperbolic  hypothesis. 
Only  a  summary  description  is  necessary,  as  the  student  will 


40  Theories  of  Parallelism 

prefer  to  peruse  its  43  paragraphs  for  himself.  Starting  from 
the  strict  definition  of  a  parallel  as  the  limiting  position  of  a 
secant,  Bolyai  proceeded  to  solid  geometry,  and  deduced  the 
existence  of  Z-lines  and  ^-surfaces  (called  by  Lobachewski 
horocycles  and  horospheres),  which  are  the  limiting  forms  of 
circles  and  spheres  of  infinite  radius  in  hyperbolic  space.  He 
found  Euclidean  geometry  to  obtain  for  horocycles  drawn  on 
horospheres ;  but  for  rectilinear  triangles  drawn  on  a  plane, 
he  proved  that  the  area  was  proportional  to  the  supplement 
of  the  angle-sum  (§  43).  The  work  merits  careful  study,  and 
comparison  with  the  corresponding  work  of  Lobachewski. 


LEGENDRE 

Reflexions  sur...la  TMorie  des  ParallUes,  Paris,  1833. 

Although  Dr  Heath  has  given  a  very  full  account  of  this 
contribution  of  Legendre's  to  the  Memoires  de  I'Institut  de 
France  (Vol.  12,  pages  367-390),  the  following  notes  on  the 
work  of  this  most  popular  Geometer  afford  opportunities  for 
independent  criticisms.  We  find  Legendre  writing: 

"  After  some  researches  undertaken  with  the  aim  of  proving 
directly  that  the  sum  of  the  angles  of  a  triangle  is  equal  to  two 
right  angles,  I  have  succeeded  first  in  proving  that  this  sum 
cannot  be  greater  than  two  right  angles.  Here  is  the  proof  as 
it  appeared  for  the  first  time  in  the  3rd  edition  of  my  Geometry 
published  in  1800." 

The  proof  proceeded  thus:  Let  P&Qz, 
be  a  series  of  identically  equal  triangles  with  their  bases 
Q-zQs,  QaQ*  •••  collinear  and  contiguous,  and  their  vertices  Plt  P2, 
P3...  on  the  same  side  of  their  bases.     If  the  angle-sum  of  a 
triangle  exceeds  a  straight  angle,  the  angle  Q^PiQ^  exceeds  the 
angle  P,Q,P2.     Therefore  P,Pa  <  Q,Q2  (Euc.  I.  18). 

Let  this  difference  be  x.  Then  if  n  is  a  number  such  that 
nx  is  greater  than  the  sum  of  the  two  sides  of  any  one  of  the 
congruent  triangles,  supposed  now  to  be  n  in  number, 

i  >  &P,  +  P,P,  +  P2P3  +  ...  +  Pn-i 


Theories  of  Parallelism  41 

i.e.  the  straight  line  is  not  the  shortest  distance  between  the 
two  points  Q!  and  Qn+1. 

The  solution  of  this  enigma  is  that  the  elliptic  hypothesis 
was  actually  assumed;  and  for  this  hypothesis,  the  straight 
line  is  re-entrant,  and  Qn+l  may  fall,  for  instance,  between  Qj 
and  Q2. 

Legendre  then  proceeded  further : 

"The  first  proposition  being  established,  it  remained  to 
prove  that  the  sum  of  the  angles  cannot  be  less  than  two 
right  angles;  but  we  must  confess  that  this  second  proposition, 
though  the  principle  of  its  proof  was  well-known  (see  Note  II, 
page  298,  of  the  12th  Edition  of  the  Elements  of  Geometry),  has 
presented  difficulties  which  we  have  not  been  able  entirely  to 
clear  away.  This  it  is  which  caused  us,  in  the  9th  Edition,  to 
return  to  Euclid's  procedure ;  and  later,  in  the  12th,  to  adopt 
another  method  of  proof  to  be  spoken  of  hereafter It  is  doubt- 
less due  to  the  imperfection  of  popular  language,  and  the 
difficulty  of  giving  a  good  definition  of  the  straight  line,  that 
Geometers  have  hitherto  achieved  little  success,  when  they 
endeavoured  to  deduce  this  Theorem  (Euc.  I.  32)  from  ideas 
purely  based  on  the  equality  of  triangles  contained  in  the  First 
Book  of  the  Elements." 

The  notion  that  the  definition  of  the  straight  line  was  in 
some  way  the  nodus  of  the  Theory  of  Parallelism  had  evidently 
occurred  to  Taurinus  and  others,  and  was  expressed  as  a  con- 
viction by  Dodgson  in  his  New  Theory  of  Parallels  (1895). 
But  contrast  Lobachewski's  judgment  (below,  page  43). 

Legendre  then  gave  a  proof  of  Euc.  I.  32  "as  it  appeared  for 
the  first  time  in  the  1st  Edition  of  my  Geometry,  published  in 
1794,  and  as  reproduced  in  the  Editions  following."  This  was 
based  on  the  following  reasoning : 

By  superposition  it  appears  that  two  triangles  are  congruent 
if  their  bases  and  both  base-angles  are  equal,  each  to  each. 
That  is,  a,  B,  C  determine  the  triangle  ABC  uniquely.  Hence 
A  =f(B,  C,  a).  Therefore  a  =  F(A,  B,  C),  say.  But  A,  B,  C 
are  pure  numbers,  if  the  right  angle  is  taken  for  unit-angle. 
Hence  a  is  obtained  as  a  pure  number.  This  is  in  fact  the 


42  Theories  of  Parallelism 

paradox  remarked  upon  by  Gauss  in  his  letter  to  Taurinus 
(above,  page  34).  Only  in  the  exceptional  case  when  a  does 
not  enter  at  all  into  the  equation  A  =f(B,  C,  a),  e.g.  when 
A  =  '7r  —  B—C,  is  there  no  unit  of  length  associated  with  any 
unit  of  angle. 

Legendre  next  gave  an  ingenious  and  elaborate  proof  that 
if  the  angle-sum  of  one  triangle  in  the  plane  is  TT,  the  angle-sum 
of  every  triangle  is  IT.  He  observed  further  that  if  the  angle- 
sum  of  a  triangle  were  greater  (less)  than  TT,  then  equidistants 
would  be  convex  (concave)  to  their  bases;  but  failed  to  make 
cogent  use  of  this  apparent  paradox,  as  it  then  was. 

His  last  attempt  to  dispose  of  the  elliptic  hypothesis  by 
manipulation  of  the  figure  of  Euc.  I.  16  was  effected  with  much 
greater  elegance  by  Lobachewski  (below,  page  44).  Legendre's 
construction  and  argument  are  given  by  Dr  Heath  in  the  first 
volume  of  his  Elements  (page  215). 


LOBACHEWSKI 

Geometrische  Untersuchungen  zur  Theorie  der  Parallel-linien, 
Berlin,  1840. 

As  Dr  Whitehead  has  said  in  one  of  his  tracts : 
"Metrical  Geometry  of  the  hyperbolic  type  was  first  dis- 
covered by  Lobachewski  in  1826,  and  independently  by  J.  Bolyai 
in  1832.  This  discovery  is  the  origin  of  the  modern  period  of 
thought  in  respect  of  the  foundations  of  Geometry "  (Axioms 
of  Descriptive  Geometry,  page  71). 

The  Geometrische  Untersuchungen  has  been  done  into  English 
by  Halsted  (Austin,  Texas,  1891). 

Characterising  Legendre's  efforts  as  fruitless,  the  Russian 
Geometer  went  on  to  say : 

"  My  first  essay  on  the  foundations  of  Geometry  was  published 
in  the  Kasan  Messenger  for  the  year  1829.... I  will  here  give  the 
substance  of  my  investigations,  remarking  that,  contrary  to  the 


Theories  of  Parallelism  43 

opinion  of  Legendre,  all  other  imperfections,  for  instance,  the 
definition  of  a  straight  line,  are  foreign  to  the  argument,  and 
without  real  influence  upon  the  Theory  of  Parallels." 

Then  followed  a  number  of  simple  theorems,  independent 
of  any  particular  theory  of  parallelism,  although  the  third 
presents  the  appearance  of  contradicting  the  elliptic  hypothesis, 
thus : 

"A  straight  line  sufficiently  prolonged  on  both  sides  proceeds 
beyond  every  limit  (iiber  jede  Grenze),  and  so  separates  a  limited 
plane  into  two  parts." 

The  ninth  of  Lobachewski's  preliminaries,  however,  did 
distinctly  assume  a  theorem  not  universally  valid  for  the 
elliptic  hypothesis: 

"  In  the  rectilinear  triangle,  a  greater  angle  lies  opposite  the 
greater  side." 

The  sixteenth  step  inaugurated  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis : 

"  16.  All  straight  lines  issuing  from  a  point  in  a  plane  can 
be  divided,  with  reference  to  a  given  straight  line  in  this  plane, 
into  two  classes,  namely,  secant  and  asecant.  The  limiting 
straight  line  between  one  class  and  the  other  is  called  parallel 
to  the  given  straight  line." 

Thus  if  Mil  is  a  parallel  to  NB  on  one  side  of  the  perpen- 
dicular MN  let  fall  from  M  upon  NB,  then  the  angle  HMN  was 
called  the  angle  of  parallelism.  Let  the  length  of  MN  be  p, 
and  denote  by  CT  the  corresponding  angle  of  parallelism  HMN, 
then  Lobachewski  established  rigorously  the  very  curious 
result : 

The  complement  of  «r  is  the  Gudermannian  of  pjK,  where 
K  is  constant  over  the  plane. 

Thus  the  angle  of  parallelism  was  determined  in  all  cases; 
and  Lobachewski's  result  was  identical  with  that  obtained  above 
on  page  xviii 

sin  vf  =  sech  p/K. 

Lobachewski's  proof  was  intricate,  however,  and  involved  the 
horocycles  and  horospheres  mentioned  already  (page  40). 


44  Theories  of  Parallelism 

Very  elegant  is  Lobachewski's  application  of  the  construction 
of  Euc.  I.  16  (itself  a  pattern  of  elegance)  to  prove  that  the 
angle-sum  of  a  triangle  cannot  exceed  two  right  angles.  Let 
ABC  be  the  triangle,  and  let  its  angle-sum  be  TT  +  e.  Take 
the  least  side  EG,  and  bisect  it  in  D.  Join  AD,  and  produce 
to  E,  so  that  DE  is  equal  in  length  to  A  D.  Then  the  triangles 
ODE,  EDA  are  superposable.  Hence  the  angle-sum  of  the 
triangle  AGE  is  7r  +  e.  Now  by  bisecting  the  side  opposite 
the  least  angle,  and  continuing  Euclid's  construction  inde- 
finitely for  each  new  triangle  obtained,  two  of  the  angles  can 

at  length  be  reduced  to  magnitudes  each  less  than  ^ ;  and  thus, 

z 

since  the  angle-sum  of  each  triangle  is  TT  +  e,  the  third  angle 
must  finally  exceed  TT. 

There  is  nevertheless  no  serious  difficulty,  provided  space  is 
of  finite  size,  as  Riemann  suggested  later. 


MEIKLE 

Theory  of  Parallel  Lines,  Edinburgh,  1844. 

The  work  of  Henry  Meikle,  published  in  the  Edinburgh 
New  Philosophical  Journal  (Vol.  36,  pages  310-318),  merits 
special  attention  for  its  sound  character,  comparative  obscurity, 
and  subsequent  fertility  in  the  hands  of  Kelland  (Transactions 
R.  S.  E.,  Vol.  23,  pages  433-450)  and  Chrystal  (Non-Euclidean 
Geometry,  Edinburgh,  1880). 

The  memoir  commenced : 

"  During  the  long  succession  of  ages  which  have  elapsed 
since  the  origin  of  Geometry,  many  attempts  have  been  made 
and  treatises  written,  though  with  little  success,  to  demonstrate 
the  important  Theorem  which  Euclid,  having  failed  to  prove, 
has  styled  his  12th  Axiom,  and  which  is  nearly  equivalent  to 
assuming  that  the  three  angles  of  every  triangle  amount  to  two 
right  angles." 

Except  that  the  elliptic  hypothesis  is  not  excluded  by  the 
Parallel-Postulate,  one  might  say  "exactly  equivalent." 


Theories  of  Parallelism  45 

The  excellence  of  Meikle's  work,  and  its  supreme  originality, 
are  attached  to  an  ingenious  and  effective  Construction,  of  which 
some  use  was  made  without  acknowledgment  in  the  Appendix 
to  our  Euclid,  Book  I.  with  a  Commentary.  This  Construction 
affords  a  demonstration  of  the  Theorem  that  triangles  of  equal 
areas  have  equal  angle-sums.  Thus : 

Let  ABC  be  any  triangle,  and  D,  E  the  middle  points  of  the 
sides  AC,  AB.  Draw  AL,  BM,  CN  perpendicular  to  DE. 
Then  the  triangles  BME,  ALE  are  congruent;  and  so  are 
the  triangles  ALD,  CND.  Hence  the  quadrilateral  BCMN 
has  both  its  area  and  its  angle-sum  equal  to  those  of  the 
triangle  ABC. 

Thus,  reversing  the  construction,  a  triangle  of  equal  area 
and  angle-sum  can  be  constructed  having  a  side  BA'  of  .any 
desired  length  not  less  than  twice  BM ;  and  then  on  BA  as 
base  can  be  constructed  an  isosceles  triangle  of  equal  area  and 
angle-sum.  In  this  way,  two  triangles  of  equal  areas  can  be 
reduced  to  isosceles  triangles  of  the  same  areas  and  angle-sums  ; 
and  on  the  same  base.  But  isosceles  triangles  of  equal  areas 
on  the  same  base  must  coincide  entirely.  Hence  the  two 
original  triangles  with  areas  equal  have  also  their  angle-sums 
equal.  Q.E.D. 

By  the  aid  of  this  magnificent  piece  of  reasoning,  Meikle 
proved  that  the  area  of  a  triangle  is  proportional  to  what  has 
been  called  its  divergence ;  but  he  rejected  the  hyperbolic 
hypothesis  on  the  ground  that  it  involved  triangles  of  finite 
area  with  zero  angles, — the  paradox  which  aroused  Gauss' 
interest  (above,  page  33). 


BOUNIAKOWSKI 

Memoires  de  l'Acaddmie...de  St  Petersbourg,  1850. 

This  writer  criticised  the  work  of  Legendre  and  Bertrarid, 
and  endeavoured  to  improve  upon  it.  He  presented  a  simple 
proof  of  the  Parallel-Postulate  in  the  following  form  : 


46  Theories  of  Parallelism 

Let  MNP  be  a  transversal  crossing  MA,  NB\  and  making 
the  angles  AMN,  BNM  together  less  than  two  right  angles. 
Then  the  angle  BNP  is  greater  than  the  angle  AMP]  and 
therefore  the  infinite  sector  BNP  is  of  greater  area  than  the 
infinite  sector  AMP.  Now  if  MA  did  not  meet  NB,  the 
infinite  sector  BNP  would  be  contained  wholly  within  the 
infinite  sector  AMP,  and  so  would  be  of  less  area.  Therefore 
MA  cannot  but  meet  NB. 

If  however  we  try  to  draw  a  figure  introducing  the  infinitely 
distant  regions  in  any  reasonable  way,  the  proof  collapses  entirely. 
Far  more  powerful  and  forcible  is  Bertrand's  demonstration  given 
above  (page  28). 


RIEMANN 

Habilitationsrede,  1854. 

Riemann's  brief  but  brilliant  and  epoch-making  Essay  was 
translated  by  Clifford  (Collected  Papers,  page  56).  The  possible 
combination  of  finite  size  and  unbounded  extent,  as  properties 
of  space,  was  indicated  in  the  words : 

"In  the  extension  of  space-construction  to  the  infinitely 
great,  we  must  distinguish  between  unboundedness  and  infinite 
extent',  the  former  belongs  to  the  descriptive  category,  the 
latter  to  the  metrical.  That  space  is  an  unbounded  threefold 
manifoldness  is  an  assumption  that  is  developed  by  every 
conception  of  the  outer  world.... The  unboundedness  of  space 
possesses... a  greater  empirical  certainty  than  any  external 
experience.  But  its  infinite  extent  by  no  means  follows  from 
this;  on  the  contrary,  if  we  assume  bodies  independent  of 
position,  and  therefore  ascribe  to  space  constant  curvature,  it 
must  necessarily  be  finite,  provided  this  curvature  has  ever  so 
small  a  value." 

The  expression  curvature  of  space  is  an  unfortunate  metaphor, 
derived  from  the  analogy  between  the  elliptic  geometry  of  the 
plane  and  the  parabolic  geometry  of  surfaces  of  uniform  curva- 


Theories  of  Parallelism  47 

ture.  The  plane  is  not  curved  for  the  elliptic,  nor  for  the 
hyperbolic  hypothesis.  Considerable  misconception  has  arisen 
in  this  way.  The  study  of  Beltrami's  analogies  rectifies  such 
an  error. 

Biemann  further  noted  the  conceivable  heterogeneity  of 
space.  The  space-constant  may  be  different  in  different  places. 
It  may  also  vary  with  the  time. 


CAYLEY 

Sixth  Memoir  upon  Qualities,  London,  1859. 

Cayley  developed  an  analytical  theory  of  Metric  which  could 
be  coordinated  to  the  three  hypotheses  which  constitute  the 
geometry  of  a  homogeneous  space.  The  hypotheses  presented 
themselves  as  the  three  cases  when  the  straight  line  has  no, 
one,  or  two  real  points  at  infinite  distance  from  all  other  points 
on  itself.  These  three  cases  are  allied  to  the  hypotheses  of  no, 
one,  or  two  parallels  from  a  given  point  to  the  straight  line. 


VON   HELMHOLTZ 

The  Essential  Principles  of  Geometry,  1866,  1868. 

Von  Helmholtz  endeavoured  to  give  new  and  precise  expres- 
sion to  the  Axioms  or  Postulates  upon  which  a  science  of  spatial 
relationships  could  be  constructed,  e.g.  perfectly  free  moveability 
of  rigid  bodies.  The  whole  of  the  ground  has  been  gone  over 
with  great  thoroughness  by  succeeding  Geometers,  notably  Lie. 
The  final  results  of  these  labours  have  been  summarised  by 
Dr  Whitehead  in  his  Tracts. 


48  Theories  of  Parallelism 

BELTRAMI 

Attempt  to  interpret  non-Euclidean  Geometry,  1868. 

Beltrami's  Saggio,  of  which  a  French  translation  was  made 
by  Hoiiel  (Annales  de  l'£cole  Normale  Superieure,  Vol.  6,  pages 
251-288),  is  of  supreme  importance  in  the  development  of  the 
Science  of  Space.  The  Italian  Geometer  proved  conclusively 
the  right  of  the  elliptic  and  hyperbolic  hypotheses  to  rank 
equally  with  the  Euclidean  system  as  theories  of  a  homogeneous 
space ;  and,  empirically,  they  are  clearly  superior.  Beltrami 
showed  this  by  pointing  out  that  all  the  elliptic  (and  hyper- 
bolic) geometry  of  the  plane  was  characterised  by  the  same 
metrical  relationships  as  hold  good  in  the  parabolic  geometry 
of  surfaces  of  uniform  positive  (and  negative)  curvature.  Any 
flaw  in  the  former  would  necessarily  be  accompanied  by  a  flaw 
in  the  latter.  If  there  is  no  flaw  in  the  Euclidean  geometry 
of  geodesies  on  a  surface  of  uniform  curvature,  then  there  can 
be  no  flaw  in  the  metabolic  geometry  of  straight  lines  on  a 
plane  surface,  for  the  metrical  relationships  are  identical.  This 
conclusive  argument  can  scarcely  be  refuted ;  Poincare'  does 
not  meet  it  in  his  La  Science  et  I'Hypothese.  It  was  there- 
fore Beltrami's  labours  which  first  established  Non-Euclidean 
Geometry  on  the  firm  foundation  whereon  it  rests  to-day, 
despite  every  kind  of  prejudice  and  misconception  which  it  has 
encountered  hitherto. 


CLIFFORD 

The  Space-Theory  of  Matter,  1870. 

Somewhat  beyond  theories  of  parallelism,  but  suggestive 
like  everything  else  of  his,  the  fragment  of  Clifford's  here  re- 
produced shows  the  freedom  of  the  Geometer  released  from  the 
fetters  of  traditionalism.  It  is  chosen  from  a  paper  embodied 
in  his  Collected  Works  (page  22) : 


Theories  of  Parallelism  49 

"  I  wish  here  to  indicate  a  manner  in  which  these  specula- 
tions (of  Riemann's)  may  be  applied  to  the  investigation  of 
physical  phenomena.  I  hold  in  fact : 

"(1)  That  small  portions  of  space  are  of  a  nature  analogous 
to  little  hills  on  a  surface  which  is  on  the  average  flat ;  namely, 
that  the  ordinary  laws  of  geometry  are  not  valid  in  them. 

"(2)  That  this  property  of  being  curved  or  distorted  is 
continually  passed  on  from  one  portion  of  space  to  another  after 
the  manner  of  a  wave. 

"  (3)  That  this  variation  of  the  curvature  of  space  is  what 
really  happens  in  that  phenomenon  which  we  call  the  motion 
of  matter  whether  ponderable  or  ethereal. 

"  (4)  That  in  the  physical  world  nothing  else  takes  place 
but  this  variation,  subject,  possibly,  to  the  law  of  continuity. 

"  I  am  endeavouring  in  a  general  way  to  explain  the  laws  of 
double  refraction  on  this  hypothesis,  but  have  not  yet  arrived  at 
any  results  sufficiently  decisive  to  be  communicated." 

The  boldness  of  this  speculation  is  surely  unexcelled  in  the 
history  of  thought.  Up  to  the  present,  however,  it  presents  the 
appearance  of  an  Icarian  flight. 


KLEIN 

Ueber  die  sogenannte  nicht-Euklidische  Geometric,  1871. 

To  Dr  Felix  Klein,  Professor  at  Gb'ttingen,  are  owed  two 
monographs  (Mathematische  Annalen,  Vol.  4,  pages  573-625 ; 
Vol.  6,  pages  112-145),  which  have  been  followed  up  by  two 
volumes  of  lectures  on  non-Euclidean  Geometry.  The  names  of 
Cayley,  Clifford  and  Klein  will  always  be  associated  with  a 
certain  view-point,  which  may  be  styled  the  analytical  theory 
of  metrical  relations. 

In  the  first  of  his  classical  Memoirs  Dr  Klein  introduced 
that  terminology  which  has  won  its  way  to  general  acceptance : 
F.  E.  4 


50  Theories  of  Parallelism 

"  The  three  Geometries  have  been  called  hyperbolic,  elliptic, 
and  parabolic,  respectively,  according  as  the  two  infinitely 
distant  points  of  the  straight  line  are  real,  imaginary,  and 
coincident"  (see  page  47  above). 

The  second  paragraph  opens  thus: 

"  All  spatial  metric  rests  upon  two  fundamental  problems, 
as  we  know  :  the  determination  of  the  distance  of  two  points 
and  of  the  inclination  of  two  straight  lines." 

The  fundamental  laws  of  linear  and  angular  measurement 
are,  in  fact :  xy  +  yz  =  xz,  with  the  proviso  that  xx  =  0 ;  so  that 
xy  +  yx  =  xx  =  0,  and  therefore  xy  =  —  yx.  These  first  principles 
of  metric  have  been  discussed  in  a  simple  but  ingenious  way  by 
Sir  Robert  Stawell  Ball  in  the  last  chapter  of  his  Theory  of 
Screws  (Cambridge,  1900). 

Klein  followed  Riemann  and  Cayley  in  the  use  of  coordinates 
to  define  position,  and  deduced  formulae  for  lengths  and  angles 
from  the  first  principles  suggested  above.  The  results,  that 
length  and  angle  are  proportional  to  the  logarithms  of  certain 
anharmonic  ratios  estimated  with  reference  to  an  Absolute 
formed  of  infinitely  distant  elements,  cannot  be  assessed  by 
Euclidean  standards,  but  belong  to  a  higher  sphere  of  research 
than  is  here  explored.  This  remark  applies  also  to  Klein's 
second  Memoir,  and  indeed  to  most  of  the  best  modern  work  in 
Non-Euclidean  Geometry. 


NEWCOMB 

Elementary  Theorems  relating  to  the  Geometry  of  a  Space 
of  three  Dimensions  and  of  uniform  positive  Curvature 
in  the  fourth  Dimension,  1877. 

The  American  Astronomer  first  assumed  the  homogeneity 
of  space  (Crelles  Journal,  Vol.  83,  pages  293-299).  Then : 

"2.  I  assume  that  this  space  is  affected  with  such  curva- 
ture that  a  right  line  shall  always  return  into  itself  at  the  end 


Theories  of  Parallelism  51 

of  a  finite  and  real  distance  2Z),  without  losing,  in  any  part  of 
its  course,  that  symmetry  with  respect  to  space  on  all  sides  of  it 
which  constitutes  the  fundamental  property  of  our  conception 
of  it." 

This  definition  of  rectilinearity  and  the  assumption  of 
firiitude  are  faultless  ;  but  no  more  needs  to  be  assumed. 
Newcomb  might  now  have  proved  that 

area/divergence  =  4Z)2/7r2  ; 

and  the  theorem  below  might  have  been  furnished  with  a 
demonstration.  Instead  of  this,  however: 

"3.  I  assume  that  if  two  right  lines  emanate  from  the 
same  point,  making  the  indefinitely  small  angle  a  with  each 
other,  their  distance  apart  at  the  distance  r  from  the  point 
of  intersection  will  be  given  by  the  equation 


_  rir 

:       n 


But,  as  was  shown  by  Dr  Chrystal,  since  area  is  by  (2) 
necessarily  proportional  to  divergence, 


,     4D*      I(M 

sdr  =  d   --  —  tan"1  -j-    , 
7T2  drj 


ITT  TTT 

Hence  s  =  A  sin  =-=:  +  B  cos  =-=  ; 

—  /  '  2iL) 


and  when  r  —  »-0,  s  —  »-0.  and  ^  --  >-«:  so  that 

dr 


B.O. 


mu  C  • 

Therefore  s  =  --  sin 

TT 


4—2 


52  TJieories  of  Parallelism 

DODGSON 

A  New  Theory  of  Parallels,  London,  1895. 

The  amiable  author  of  Alice  in  Wonderland  contributed  to 
the  Theory  of  Parallelism  a  pretty  substitute  for  the  Fifth 
Postulate,  as  follows: 

"  In  every  circle,  the  inscribed  equilateral  tetragon  is  greater 
than  any  one  of  the  segments  which  lie  outside  it." 

Dodgson's  Axiom  was  aimed  at  the  exclusion  of  the  hyper- 
bolic hypothesis,  in  which  the  assertion  is  not  universally 
correct. 

For  consider,  on  the  hyperbolic  plane,  a  circle  of  very  great 
radius  nK,  where  n  is  a  large  number,  and  two  perpendicular 
diameters  A  OA ',BOB'. 

The  area  of  the  circle  is 

rnK  x 

2-7T  I       K  sinh  ^dx=  2?rif2  (cosh  n  —  1), 
Jo  -"- 

which  approaches  the  limit  irK2en,  as  n  increases  indefinitely. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  area  of  the  quadrilateral  formed  by 
the  points  A,  A',  B,  B'  is 

4K2 1|  -  2  tan-1  (sech 

AO 
because  cos  ABO  =  cosh  -~-  sin  OAB  (above,  page  xviii).     And 

as  n  increases,  this  approaches  the  limit 

(20-"),  i.e. 


Whence  it  appears  that  the  area  of  a  segment  is  ultimately 
infinitely  greater  than  the  area  of  the  tetragon. 


FIRST  ADDITIONAL  NOTE 

ANALYTICAL  GEOMETRY  FOR  THE  METABOLIC  HYPOTHESES 

FROM  very  simple  synthetic  results,  the  most  comprehensive 
analytical  formulae  for  Metabolic  Geometry  can  be  secured. 
These  formulae  of  general  application  will  be  proved  for  the 
elliptic  hypothesis,  and  the  corresponding  forms  for  the 
hyperbolic  hypothesis  will  be  interpolated  as  occasion  arises. 

The  principal  assumptions  are  (i)  that  the  area  of  a  triangle 
is  k?  (or  K2)  times  its  divergence,  and  (ii)  that  the  straight  line 
is  in  general  a  line  of  minimum  length  between  any  two  of  its 
points.  The  groundwork  of  our  Introduction,  along  with  an 
argument  similar  to  that  of  Euc.  I.  16-20,  justifies  these 
assumptions,  to  which  may  be  added  the  observation  that 
Euclidean  geometry  holds  good  within  any  infinitesimal  area 
of  a  homogeneous  plane. 

Adhering  then,  for  convenience,  to  the  Elliptic  Hypothesis, 
let  r  be  the  radius  vector,  &  the  vectorial  angle,  and  <f>  the 
inclination  of  the  tangent  to  the  radius  vector  for  any  point  of 
a  curve.  Let  0  be  the  pole,  and  P,  P1  the  points  of  contact 
of  two  consecutive  tangents  to  the  curve,  inclined  at  an 
infinitesimal  angle  d\}r.  Let  RdO  be  the  area  of  the  triangle 
OPP',  where  R  is  a  function  of  r  at  present  unknown.  Then 
by  (i),  to  the  first  order  of  infinitesimals, 

RdO  =  k*(d8  +  TT  -  (f>  +  <j>  +  d(f>  +  TT  -  d^r  -  2-Tr) 


54  Theories  of  Parallelism 

Let  t  be  a  parameter  for  the  point  P  of  the  curve,  then  this 
result  becomes 


In  particular,  for  the  points  of  a  straight  line  ^  =  0,  and  so 


Again  by  (ii)  we  have  for  the  straight  line 

t  =  0, 


where  s  is  the  length  of  the  arc  of  the  curve  measured  from 
one  of  its  points.  And  the  infinitesimal  length  of  the  per- 
pendicular from  P  upon  OP'  is  R'dO,  where  the  dash  denotes 
differentiation  for  r,  —  because  the  product  of  dr  and  R'dO  gives 
the  correct  value  dRdO  for  the  element  of  area  in  polar  co- 
ordinates. Thus,  for  a  straight  line, 


) 


Hence,  by  the  Calculus, 

d  r     R'R"62 
dil~       §     ' 

and  —  =  0, 

at     s 

where  dots  denote  differentiation  for  the  parameter  t. 

r                   R'd 
But  cos  6  =  - ,     sin  d>  = , 

s  s 

so  that  we  have 

-T-  (cos  </>)  =  R"6  sin  <£,  -r.(R'  sin  <£)  =  0. 

Thus   j>  =  -R"0,     R'sm(j)  =  P,     where    P   is  the    value 
assumed  by  the  function  R'  when  r=p,  p   being   the  per- 


Theories  of  Parallelism 


55 


pendicular  from  0  on  the  straight  line.     These  two  results  are 
not  independent,  of  course. 

But,  for  a  straight  line,  k*  (j>  +  (k*  -  R)  6  =  0. 

Therefore   k2R"+  R  —  k2  =  0  ;  and  by  differentiation  for  r, 


I  I 

Integrating,  R'  =  L  cos  r  +  M  sin  7,    where  L  and  M   are 

K  K 

independent  of  r. 

Remembering  that  for  r=0,  R'  =  0;  and  that  for  r  small, 

T 

R'  =  r,  we  see  that  R  —  k  sin  T . 

K 

Hence  for  the  straight  line,  as  considered, 

j    •    r   .  i    •    P 

k  sin  j  sin  9  =  k  sin  j- ; 

rC  /C 

that  is,  in  a  right-angled  triangle  of  hypothenuse  r,  wherein  p 
is  the  length  of  the  side  opposite  the  angle  <f>, 

.    r    .     ,        .    p 

sin  r  sin  d>  =  sin  ,- . 

/  •  /  • 

A/  iv 

T      .  T) 

[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis,  sinh  ~sin  <£  =  smh  ^.. 
Also  we  find  now  for  any  curve 


ds*  =  dr*  +  A?  sin2  T  .  d&\ 

K 

,      .      T       dB 

tan  <p  =  k  sin  T  .  ^—  , 
k    dr 


T 

=  COS  y  . 
K 


[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 


. 
zt 


„  .  ,     r    dO 
tan  <b  =  K  smh  -TT  •  'f~  > 
K   dr 

T        '         * 

ir  =  cosh  j.  8  +  <>. 


56  Theories  of  Parallelism 

/j\  fp 

We  prove  next  that  tan  ^  =  tan  j-  cos  0. 

K  K 

d0        1  T  .  .     TO  T 

In  fact,  -J-  —  -J-  cosec  r  tan  <f> ;  and  sin  <£  =  sin  ^  cosec  T  5 

CtT*       K  fC  1C  K 


so  that 


T  dv  r 

k  -j-  =  cosec  -r 

dr  k 


n  T 

=  cosec2  T  /  A  /  cosec2  y  —  cosec2  -r 


7        /        A    /         V^WU^V-'         T      V-*-/O^S--         , 

«/  V  k  k 


T    I      I        n  T 

=  cosec2  T  /  A  /  cot2  y-  -  cot2T ; 
«/    V          A;  A;' 

/          T    I  1)\ 

whence  6  —  a.  =  cos"1  cot  T  /  cot  \    • 

V      */        k) 

f)  T 

and  so  tan^-  =  tan  j  cos  (0  —  a). 

K  K 

n  T 

[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis,  tanh  ^  =  tanh  ^  cos  (6  —  a). 

A  xt 

Hence  if  the  perpendicular  p  from  0  upon  any  straight 
line  is  inclined  at  angle  a  to  the  axis  Ox  from  which  the 
vectorial  angle  0  is  measured, 

D  T 

tan  ^  =  tan  T  cos  (6  —  a). 

We  can  next  find  the  length  P'P"  between  the  points 
(r'6r)  and  (r"6").  Using  the  result  just  obtained,  along  with 

T  ' 

$  =  k  sin  T  cosec  <£ .  0,  we  get 

K 


P'P"  =  k  tan?  sec? 


•6" 


d0 


uuo  ^i/   —  w/     i     uodi     y 

J  & 

Adopting  tan  ^  tan  (0  —  a)  for  variable,  and  integrating, 

P'P"  =  k  I    tan-1  {sin  £  tan  (0  -  a)l . 
Jv  \      k  '] 


Theories  of  Parallelism  57 


sin  ^  (tan  0"  -  a.  -  tan  6'  -  a) 
I.e.,          tan  — y- 


1  +  sin2 1  tan  (ff  -  a)  tan  (0"  -  a) 

a  result  presently  transformed  into 

P'P"  r'        r"  r>        r"  t 

cos  — j —  =  cos  y  cos  y—  +  sin  —  sin  y-  cos  (0  —  6  ), 

A?  K  K  K  K 

which  manifests  the  analogy  between  the  elliptic  geometry  of 
the  plane  and  the  parabolic  geometry  of  the  sphere. 
[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 

P'P"  r'  r"  r'          r" 

cosh     „     =  cosh  -^  cosh  -^  —  sinh  ^  sinh  -~  cos  (ff—  0"). 

J\.  Ji.  Ji  XL  XL 

Let  us  now  adopt  Escherich's  Coordinates.     Let  Ox,  Oy  be 
two  perpendicular  axes  ;  PM  and  P^  the  perpendiculars  upon 

,  .  ,   p         ,      ..  OJf  0^ 

them  trom  any  point  r  ;  and  write  x  =  tan  —7—,  y  =  tan  — y—. 

A?  K 

,  OM  .  ON 

[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis,  x=  tanh  -j=-,  y  =  tanh  -^-. 

We  then  have  at  once 

PF  \+xx'  +  yy 

COS  —j—  =    -p=== .  (I). 

l.t  ./-i.o.n./-i.frt«/rt  ^      ' 


[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 


cosh 


PP'  \—xx—  yy' 


V 1  -  of  -  y*  V 1  -  x*  -  y'2 ' 


Choosing   consecutive    points,    x'  =  x  +  dx,  y'  =  y  +  dy,   we 
have 


[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 

,    _  rr2  da?  +  dy*  -  (xdy  -  ydxf 


58  Theories  of  Parallelism 

1}  T 

Also,  from  tan  j-  =  tan  y  cos  (6  —  a),  obtained  above,  we  now 

1C  K 

have 

T  T         fir        \  n 

tan  T  cos  0  cos  a  +  tan  r  cos  (  -  —  0 }  sin  a  =  tan  y  , 
k  k        \2        J  k 

showing    that    the    equation    of  the    straight    line   in   these 
coordinates  is    x  cos  a  +  y  sin  a  =  constant ;  or,  in  general, 

ax  +  by+c  =  Q (II) 

where  a,  b,  c  are  any  constants. 

We  may  next  determine  the  angle  of  intersection  of  the  two 
straight  lines  ax  +  by  +  c  =  0,  a'x  +  b'y  +  c  =  0. 

Let  P  be  their  point  of  intersection,  with  coordinates  x,  y ; 
and  Q,  ty  consecutive  points  of  the  two  lines,  with  coordinates 
(x  +  e&,  y  —  ea)  and  (x  +  e'b',  y  —  ea),  where  e  and  e'  are  y^ery 
small. 

Then  the  angle  ^  required  is  determinable  from  the 
application  of  the  Euclidean  formula  to  the  infinitesimal 
triangle  QPQ', 

QQ>*  =  PQ*  +  PQ'*  -  2PQ  .  PQ'.  cos  QPQ. 
Hence,  omitting  a  common  denominator, 


-  e'6')2  +  (ea  -  eV)2  +  (x .  ea  -  eV  +  y.eb-  e'bj 

=  (e&)2  +  (ea)2  +  (a? .  ea  +  y  .  eft)2  +  (e'6')2  +  (e'aj 
+  (x .  ea'  +  y .  e'&')2  -  2  cos  x 


x  Ve2^  +  e2a2  +  (ea#  +  efa/)2  .  V  e/26'2  +  e/2a'2  +  (e'a'x  +  e'6't/)2. 
But  ax  +  by=  —  c)  and  a'x  +  b'y  =  —  c'  ;  and  so 

aa  +  bb'  +  cc' 

cosv=    ..  =  —  .  = 

Va2  +  62  +  c2.  Va'2  +  6/2  +  c'2 

[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 

aa'  +  bb'  —  cc' 


cos  v  = 


In  particular,  then,  the  straight  lines  are  perpendicular,  if 
aa'  +  bb'  +  cc'  =  0. 


Theories  of  Parallelism  59 

[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 

aa'  +  bb'  -  cc  =  0. 

Calling  u,  v  the  coordinates  of  a  straight  line  ux  +  vy  —  1  =  0, 
the  angle  between  the  consecutive  lines  (u,  v)  (u  +  du,  v  +  dv) 
is  given  by 

2  _  du*  +  dv1  +  (udv  —  vduf 


[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 

,  2_  du2  +  dv2  —  (udv  —  vduf 
X  =  (1  -  w2  -  v2)2 

We  now  only  need  further  (and  only  for  convenience'  sake) 
to  determine  the  length  of  the  perpendicular  p'  from  (x'y) 
upon  ax  +  by  +  c  =  0.  This  is  derivable  from  results  I,  II 
and  III ;  suggesting  that  these  contain  the  entire  metric  of  the 
elliptic  plane  in  analytical  form.  The  coordinates  of  the  foot 
of  the  perpendicular  are  found  by  II  and  III  to  be 

(Dx^P^a     Dy'  -  P'fr 
VlJ^TFc"  '     D-P'c  )  ' 

where  D  =  a2  +  b2  +  c-,    P'  =  ax  +  by'  +  c. 

Thus  oos^--      AD(l +#'2  +  2/'2)  — -f2 

1  11U>  LfUa    ,     —        /     — 2 — — . 

k      V       (1  +  a;'2  +  y'*)D 

,                    .    p                   ax'  +  by'  +  c  ,T  VN 

whence          sin  y-  =- —  —  (IV). 

*       v  a2  +  62  +  c2  V  1  +  x'*  +  y'2 
[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 

.   ,    p                  ax'  +  by'  +  c 
smh  £=  =  -  f 


Any  problem  in  Metabolic  Geometry  may  be  attacked  by 
means  of  results  I — IV  thus  secured. 

For  instance,  the.  equation  of  a  Circle  of  centre  (£>;)  and 
radius  p  is  by  I 

(1  +  far  +  rjyy-  =  cos2 .  (1  +  f  +  rf)  (1  +  &  +  y2). 


60  Themes  of  Parallelism 

[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 


[Letting  £  =  0,  tj  =  tanh  ~,  and  p  become  indefinitely  great, 
XL 

the  equation  of  a  Horocycle  touching  Ox  at  0  is  obtained: 
(l-2/)2=l-^-2/2. 

The  equation  to  an  Equidistant  of  axis  ax  +  by  +  c  =  0  at 
distance  OT  is  by  IV 

(ax  +  by  +  c)2  =  sin2  ?  .  (a2  +  62  +  c2)  (1  +  a?  +  f). 
[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 

(ox  +  %  +  c)2  =  sinh2  J.  .  (a2  +  62  -  c2)  (1  -  a?  -  f). 

A  result  of  considerable  beauty  and  interest  is  an  expression 
for  the  measure  of  curvature.  If  de  is  the  angle  between  the 
normals  at  the  extremities  of  an  infinitesimal  arc  ds  of  any 

curve,  and  the  radius  of  curvature  p  is  defined  by  -7-  =  Arsin  £ 

then  if  t  is  the  parameter  of  a  point  on  the  curve,  formulae 
I  and  III  give 

.o      .  ...... 

cot  I  =  <^  -  *y 

[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 

p      ...         .,  f        l-tf2-v2 
coth  ^.  =  (xy  —  xy)  \  —  —  -.  —  ,    .      . 
K  'x*  +   *-x-x 


Applied  to  the  equation  of  the  equidistant  to  Ox  at  distance 

8,  namely  : 

s 

2/2  =  (l+#2)tan2  -, 

rC 

or  parametrically, 

x  =  tan  t,     y  =  tan  j-  .  sec  i, 

A> 


Theories  of  Parallelism  61 

the  curvature-formula  gives 


suggesting  that  the  curve  is  a  circle  of  radius  -=  —  8. 

i! 

Evidently  the  results  given  in  this  brief  Note  are  sufficient 
to  furnish  occupation  for  innumerable  leisure  hours,  in  the 
extension  of  the  usual  results  of  Analytical  Geometry  to  the 
metabolic  hypotheses.  The  following  Note  will  also  furnish 
the  materials  for  extending  Analytical  Dynamics  so  that  it 
may  apply  to  a  space  whose  geometry  is  metabolic. 


SECOND   ADDITIONAL  NOTE 

PLANETARY  MOTION  FOR  THE  METABOLIC  HYPOTHESES 

THE  difficulties  introduced  into  the  Newtonian  theory  of 
planetary  orbits  by  the  adoption  of  either  of  the  metabolic 
hypotheses  of  space  are  far  from  insuperable.  Let  us  assume 

LL  T* 

j-  cosec2  T  as   the  law  of  gravitational   force,   for  the  elliptic 

Kr  K 

hypothesis.  We  can  then  prove  that  the  polar  equation  of  a 
planetary  orbit,  with  the  sun  for  pole,  and  an  apsidal  distance 
d  for  axis,  is  simply 

k  _  1  4-  e  cos  6 
~d~  ~l+e      ' 

COt  y 
K 

and  that  if 

major  axis  of  orbit 

- 

then  the  periodic  time  is 


^  1  +  a-  ' 
[For  the  Hyperbolic  Hypothesis, 

T 

coth  j,     .,  a 

_  K     1  +  e  cos  6 

7d=       1+6      ; 
coth  -T*. 

Ji 

periodic  time, 


Vjil-o" 

where 

/major  axis  of  orbitN 


Theories  of  Parallelism  63 

In  what   follows  we   adhere    to   the   Elliptic    Hypothesis. 
The  results  obtained  in  the  First  Note  (page  55)  give  for  the 

radial  velocity  :  r ;   and  for  the  transverse  velocity  :  k  sin  -r  6 ; 

K 

in  the  case  of  a  particle  whose  polar  coordinates  are  (r,  6). 

Applying  the  usual  method,   we  find  for  the  increase   of 
radial  velocity  in  time  dt  from  P  to  P' 

rdt  —  k  sin  y  Q  cos  G>, 

where  to  is  the  angle  made  with  OP  by  the  perpendicular  to 

OP'  at  P'. 

OP'  r  r  • 

But     cos  w  =  cos  —j—  sin  POP'  =  cos  -r.d&  =  cos  y  6  .  dt,    to 

the  first  order,  by  the  last  formula  on  page  xviii  above.     Thus 
the  radial  acceleration  is 

V  T      ' 

r  —  k  sin  y  cos  y  .  6* (I). 


Similarly  again  the  increase  of  transverse  velocity  in  time 

dt  is 

d  I          T  '\ 

-r- 1  k  sin  T  0 } .  dt  +  r  cos  «', 

dt\         K    J 

where  a/  is  the  angle  made  with  OP'  by  the  perpendicular  to 

OP  at  P. 

OP  r  • 

But  cos  o>'=  cos  -j- .  d6  =  cos  y  6  dt  (page  xviii). 

Hence  the  transverse  acceleration  is 

/            rdf'«rA\  TT 

k  cosec  7  -7;  sin2  T  0}  (11). 

k  dt  \       k    J 

It  is  clear  also  that  if  <£  is  the  inclination  of  the  velocity  v 

to  the  radius  r, 

r  0 
tan  <j>  =  k  sin  j  - (III). 

K  T 

The  areal  velocity  is 

(IV). 


64  Theories  of  Parallelism 

And  the  kinetic  energy  of  a  particle  of  mass  m  is 

(V). 


j 


Thus  for  a  particle  of  unit  mass  acted  upon  only  by  a  radial 
force  R  towards  the  origin, 

T  T    ' 

r  —  k  sin  -r  cos  T^  =  —  R, 

T    d  f  T   "\ 

k  cosec  7-  -7-  ( sin2  T  6  }  =  0. 
k  at  \       k   J 

T    ' 

Hence  &*  sin2  y  0  =  h,  where  h  is  a  constant  for  the  orbit ; 
and  the  energy-equation  is  found  to  be 


r"  +  fc2  sin2  £  02  =  C-  2  f  '  Rdr. 


It  appears  that  if  a  metabolic  hypothesis  of  space  holds 
good,  equal  areas  are  not  described  in  equal  times  in  central 
orbits.  What  transverse  force  must  be  introduced  for  the 
retention  of  the  Newtonian  Law  ?  If  we  are  to  secure  that 


the  transverse  force  is  determined  by  the  value  of  the  trans- 
verse acceleration  to  be 

r  d  (  .  „  r  i\ 
k  cosec  T  -T-    sin2  T  6 
k  dt\       k    J 

r  d  f.  r 

=  kH  cosec  r  -j-    1  -f  cos  T 

k  dt\  k 

=  -Hr; 

so  that  there  must  be  a  transverse  retardation  proportional  to 
the  radial  velocity.  This  would  not  be  produced  by  frictional 
forces  of  the  usual  kind. 


Theories  of  Parallelism  65 

Considering  now  the  earth's  orbit  about  the  sun,  let  us 

ill  V 

assume  R  =  ~  cosec2  r ,  corresponding  to  the  law  of  potential 

K  K 

(extended  from  Poisson's): 


where  p  is  the  density  of  a  material  medium. 

r 

j 
k 


•       h  i* 

Then  when  we  substitute   Q  =  j^  cosec2  7,  the  equation  of 


energy  becomes 

r  2  +    J  cosec2     _       cot     =  2E,  say. 


Thus 


h  r  , 

TT  cosec2  T  dr 

n  n 

whence      dO  = 


j 


T     h2 


1        r 

Write  conveniently  -ar  for  T  cot  -r,  then 


2E 


0-a  = 


Write  also  o-  for  OT  —    2,  and  /2  for  --  —      +    -,  then 


and  so  <r  =  f  cos  ($  ~~  a)- 

If  we  measure  ^  from  the  apsidal  line,  and  write  d,  u  for 
an  apsidal  distance  and  corresponding  velocity,  then 

h  =  kusm-r,    2E  =  u*—  -77  cot  T. 
F.  E.  5 


66  Theories  of  Parallelism 

Thus 

,     I       d        fj,  -d 

/=  7cot  T  --  %-j-  cosec2  j  ; 
J      k       k     i(2k2  k 

and  we  get 

,  r       /*  -d      /     .d       At  d\ 

cot  T  —  c?  cosec2  T  =   cot  T  --  -r  cosec2  r  cos  0. 
A;     u?k  k      \       k     u*k  k} 

Now  write 

u2k  .    d        d 

e  —  —  sin  T  cos  T  —  1, 

/*        «       « 

so  that  e  is  positive  or  negative  according  as  the  centripetal 
force  at  the  apse  is  less  or  greater  than  for  the  description  of  a 
circle  ;  then 


(1  +  e)  —  -5  =  1  +  e  cos  0, 

,  d> 

COt  7 

k 

the  equation  of  the  earth's  orbit  about  the  sun,  if  space  is  of 
finite  extent. 

The  equation  of  this  orbit  in  Escherich's  coordinates,  with  a 
suitable  change  of  origin  along  the  apsidal  line,  is  reducible  to 
the  form 


so  that  the  orbit  has  a  geometrical  centre. 

The  curve  then  exhibits  several  properties,  precisely 
analogous  to  those  of  the  ellipse  in  parabolic  geometry,  obtain- 
able by  formulae  I-IV  of  the  First  Note. 

Three  of  these  properties  may  be  indicated  thus  : 

(1)  SP+ST  =  AA', 

SP  PM 

(2)  sin  -y-  cosec  — : —  =  constant, 

k  k 

SY  .    S'Y' 

(3)  sin  -r-  sm  — j-—  =  constant. 


Theories  of  Parallelism  67 

/major  axis  of  orbitA 
If  now  we  write  a  =  tan  (  -        — =T —        -  ) ,  we  have  the 

formula   analogous    to    a    well-known    result    in    Newtonian 
dynamics : 


Let  us  proceed  further  to  find  the  periodic  time  in  the 
orbit,  T ;  that  is,  the  length  of  the  year  if  space  is  of  finite 
extent. 

h  {  T\ 

Since    6  =  r^  1 1  +  cot2  -r ) ,   we   have  by  use   of  the   polar 

K    \  K  / 

equation  of  the  orbit  found  above 

d  2ir 

Acot2r 

A         ,/• 


(1  +  ef  tan2  ^  +  (1  +  e  cos  &? 

i  ™ 

In    addition    to   a   as   defined    already,   let   us   introduce 

OS 

c  =  tan  -j- ,  where  G  is  the  centre  of  symmetry  and  S  the  centre 

K 

of  force  for  the  orbit. 

Then  the  four  following  equivalences  are  true : 

u,  a  +  c  1  4-  a2     ,  „     ak  a2  —  c2 


t      •— •    "T  --     ~       j-  ,      —  » 

K  a  —  c     a  al  +  c2 

^dl  +  ac  cl+a2 

cot  7  = ,  e  =  -  = . 

fc      a  —  c  al+c2 

The  value  of  T  can  now  be  transformed  thus : 


It  is  therefore  necessary  to  evaluate  the  definite  integral 

f      " 

where 

P=-^ 


68  Theories  of  Parallelism 

Express   then    this    integral    as    the    difference    of    two 
conjugate  integrals: 

2"          de  *"          d6 


_L_  I  f2"          de  [* 

2iP\Jo  RcosB  +  Q-iP     J0 


each  of  which  may  be  evaluated  by  the  application  of  Cauchy's 
Theorem  to  a  contour  in  the  2-plane  (z  =  ei6),  consisting  of  a 
circle  of  unit  radius  about  the  origin. 
Thus 

M  =  2_  f  dz 

cose  +  Q-iP     iR    -     9Q-iP          ' 

I  Z   +  £t  -  jj  -  •2  +  1 
/  Jt 

where    the   second    integral   is   along   the   unit-circle   in   the 
2-plane. 

Q  —  iP 

Now  z*  +  2       „  —  z  +  1  is  identically  equal  to 

Q-iP     H     .\/       Q-iP     H     . 

~ 


where  H<  =  (Q2-  E2  -  P2)2  +  (2P£)2,  and  tan  2^,  = 


The  product  of  the  moduli  of  the  poles  (a,  /3)  of  the  integral 
is  unity,  since  a/3  =  1  ;  and  therefore  only  one  of  these  poles 
lies  within  the  unit-circle. 

Moreover,  the  integrand 


Q-iP     H     .  Q-iP     H     .  y 


Hence,  by  Cauchy's  Theorem,  inasmuch  as  there  is  but  one 
simple  pole  within  U|  =  l,  the  contour-integral  above  has  the 
value 

2          .Re*"     2-7T  , 


Theories  of  Parallelism 

Hence  also 


_     a — *<» 

'"~  H        ' 


Therefore 

de  2?r 


f 

-  o 


. 

toa  _  />—  i<a\ 


27T 


Thus 
'2*  de 


]  a*~^ 

V(i  + 


-C2     )2    .     L     ,    Cl  +  a\030\ 


(1  +  a2)^  '    a2  -  c2     '  (a2  -  c2)^  (1  +  a2 


(l+a2)(a2-c2) 
Finally, 


V/A  1  +  a2 

If  the  straight  line  had  a  complete  length  as  great  as 
25,000  light-years,  the  quantitative  difference  between  the 
length  of  the  year  deduced  from  this  formula  and  the 
Newtonian  result  for  Euclidean  space  would  be  an  incon- 
ceivably small  fraction  of  a  second. 

But  the  formal  difference  between  the  old  and  new  results 
is  considerable. 


70 


Theories  of  Parallelism 


POSTSCRIPT 
It  will  be  observed  that  by  use  of  the  formula 

0  27T 


r 

Jo 


COS  i 


the   preceding  analysis  may  be  more  rapidly  worked  out  as 
follows : 


a*  (1  +  a2)2  ac2  „, 

~~ i  •  J-  == 


f 

Jo 


dd 


c  1  +  aV       c2  (1+  a2)2 


.  c  (1  +  a2)  f2jr 
i»    a2  -  c2    I 

7  o 


cos 


a(l+c2)-i(a2-c2) 
c(l+a2) 


cos  ^  + 


+  a2) 


1  c(l+a2)r     27 
"2t    a2-c2    L(0i_ 

27rac2(l  +a2) 


27rc(l+t'a) 


(a2  - 


which  furnishes  the  desired  result. 


CAMBRIDGE    UNIVERSITY    PRESS 

The  Thirteen  Books  of  Euclid's  Elements.  Translated  from 
the  text  of  Heiberg.  With  Introduction  and  Commentary. 
By  T.  L.  HEATH,  C.B.,  Sc.D.,  sometime  Fellow  of  Trinity 
College,  Cambridge.  In  three  volumes.  Royal  8vo.  42s.  net. 

"Dr  Heath  has  performed  with  great  care  his  task  of  translating  the 
Elements.  His  notes,  critical  and  historical,  display  an  acquaintance  with 
every  author,  ancient  or  modern,  who  has  dealt  with  the  origin  of  mathe- 
matical science ;  and  he  has  well  earned  the  gratitude  with  which  his  work 
will  be  received  by  all  earnest  students." — Athenaeum. 

"No  mathematician,  unless  quite  without  historical  and  philosophical 
sense,  can  fail  to  be  delighted  with  Dr  Heath's  edition  of  Euclid.  For  it  is 
not  merely  the  first  and  only  English  translation  of  the  famous  '  definitive  MS.' 
of  Heiberg,  but  in  three  beautifully  printed  volumes  it  brings  together  in  a  most 
masterful  exposition  the  results  of  critical  inquiry  from  pre-Euclidean  times 
down  to  the  very  latest  European  researches  in  the  foundations  of  geometry. 
It  is  indeed  a  work  that  neither  geometrician  nor  philosopher  can  afford  to 
ignore." — Nation,  New  York. 

"  Those  who  are  really  interested  in  Greek  geometry  will  be  deeply  grateful 
to  Dr  Heath  for  putting  together,  in  such  an  attractive  form,  such  a  large 
amount  of  historical  information,  and  thus  saving  students  from  an  immense 
amount  of  toilsome  research." — Nature. 


Royal  Society  of  London.  Catalogue  of  Scientific  Papers, 
1800 — 1900.  Subject  Index.  Volume  I,  Pure  Mathe- 
matics. Royal  8vo.  pp.  Iviii  +  666.  Buckram,  21s.  net ; 
half-pigskin,  27s.  net. 

"  The  volume  contains  nearly  40,000  references,  distributed  amongst 
700  different  serials.  The  list  of  libraries  in  this  country  in  which  these 
serials  may  be  seen  will  save  many  a  fruitless  journey  to  the  student.... It  is 
almost  superfluous  to  add  that  the  volumes  of  this  series  should  figure  in  every 
scientific  library,  and  that  this  one  in  particular  will  be  invaluable  to  every 
mathematician." — Athenaeum. 

"  The  output  of  the  scientific  world  is  now  so  great  that  considerable 
attention  has  been  devoted  of  late  to  devising  means  of  acquainting  those 
engaged  in  scientific  research  with  the  results  attained  by  other  investigators. 
With  the  publication  of  the  first  volume  of  the  Royal  Society  Index,  the  student 
of  mathematics  is  now  particularly  well  provided  in  this  respect... and  at  a 
moderate  estimate  it  will  lessen  the  labour  of  forming  bibliographies,  or  of 
hunting  up  references,  by  considerably  more  than  one-half." — Nature. 


CAMBRIDGE  UNIVERSITY  PRESS,  FETTER  LANE,  LONDON. 


Cnmlinliijr: 

PRINTED    BY    JOHN   CLAY,    M.A. 
AT   THE    DNIVEB8ITY   PBESS. 


UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA  LIBRARY 

Los  Angeles 
This  book  is  DUE  on  the  last  date  stamped  below. 


JUL  1 7  1950 

.B**1 

>,  8 1S5T 


MAY  4    1961 


JAN  3  - 1962 
BOOK  BOX 
1961 


APR  3  0  1966 
MAY  *  1 1965 


Form  L9 — 15m-10,'48(B1039)444 


MAT  2  ft  1369 

MAY  2?REC'0 

JUN  1  6  1969 


JIM.  7 


SEP  9     1969 


LTBRARY 


Engine 

Malta 

Scie 

Libi 


A    000165696    6 


AUXIU/Wf 

STACK 


72 


E  SEVEN  BOOKHUNTERS 

JTIONO.  BOX  22,  NEW  YORK  II.N.Y. 
Out-of-Print  Books