Skip to main content

Full text of "The study of nature and the vision of God : with other essays in philosophy"

See other formats


//x 


THE    STUDY   OF   NATURE   AND    THE   VISION 

OF   GOD  :    WITH  OTHEE  ESSAYS 

IN  PHILOSOPHY 


Then,  if  that  is  his  motive,  he  will  not  be  a  statesman. 

By  the  dog  of  Egypt,  he  will !  in  the  city  which  is  his  own  he 
certainly  will,  though  in  the  land  of  his  birth  perhaps  not,  unless  he 
have  a  divine  call. 

I  understand ;  you  mean  that  he  will  be  a  ruler  in  the  city  of 
which  we  are  the  founders,  and  which  exists  in  idea  only  ;  for  1  do 
not  believe  that  there  is  such  an  one  anywhere  on  earth  ? 

In  heaven,  I  replied,  there  is  laid  up  a  pattern  of  it,  methinks, 
which  he  who  desires  may  behold,  and  beholding,  may  set  his  own 
house  in  order.  But  whether  such  an  one  exists,  or  ever  will  exist  in 
fact,  is  no  matter ;  for  he  will  live  after  the  manner  of  that  city, 
having  nothing  to  do  with  any  other. 

I  think  so,  he  said. 

—Plato,  Republic,  592  (tr.  Jowett). 


The  Study  of  Nature  and  the  Vision  of  God 
with  Other  Essays  in  Philosophy 


BY 

GEORGE   JOHN    BLEWETT 

Ryerson    Professor    of  Moral    Philosophy    in    Victoria    College,    Toronto 
Sometime  Rogers  Memorial  Fellow  of  Harvard  University 


^       I 
TORONTO  *^\  \ 

WILLIAM    BRIGGS 


M  CM  VII 


Entered  according  to  Act  of  the  Parliament  of  Canada,  in  the  year  one  thousand  nine  hundred 
and  seven,  by  GEORGE  JOHN  BLEWETT,  at  the  Department  of  Agriculture. 


MORTVIS   MEIS 


PREFACE. 

IN  the  endeavour  of  man  to  draw  near  to  that  ultimate  reality 
with  which  it  is  his  salvation  to  make  himself  at  one — the  endeavour 
which  is  on  its  practical  side  religion,  on  its  theoretical  side  philos 
ophy  and  theology — there  is  an  elemental  distinction  between  two 
tendencies  or  methods.  The  one,  to  find  God,  denies  the  world.  The 
other  retains  the  world,  but  when  God  is  found  the  world  becomes 
new ;  or  rather,  in  finding  God  the  world  also  is  found,  for  the  knowl 
edge  of  God  is  the  ultimate  truth  about  the  world.  To  trace  these 
tendencies,  in  the  broad  outline  of  their  historical  relations  of  con 
flict  and  of  combination,  was  once  the  hope  of  the  present  writer. 
Such  a  study,  if  it  could  have  been  undertaken  successfully,  would 
have  done  two  things:  would  have  cast  light  on  the  forms  which  in 
human  history  the  religious  endeavour  to  be  at  one  with  God  has 
assumed;  and  would  have  marked  out  for  students,  in  an  elementary 
but  yet  fundamental  way,  the  ground-currents  of  the  history  of 
philosophy  and  theology.  But  it  is  now  almost  certain  that  that 
plan  will  never,  even  in  briefest  outline,  be  carried  through ;  and  so  a 
number  of  essays,  written  at  different  times  and  under  different 
circumstances  as  studies  toward  it,  are  published  here  as  separate 
papers.  Each  can  be  read  by  itself;  yet,  since  there  is  enough  of 
the  original  plan  in  the  separate  parts  to  give  them  a  certain  unity, 
it  would  be  better  to  take  them  together  as  forming  a  single  historical 
discussion.  For  this  reason  a  short  introduction  has  been  prefixed, 
stating  the  main  point  of  the  discussion  and  the  relation  of  each  of 
the  papers  to  it. 

The  essay  on  Spinoza  is  the  property  of  Harvard  University,  and 
is  published  here  by  permission  of  President  Eliot.1  This  is  only  a 
single  instance  of  the  kindness  with  which  through  many  years  that 
great  university  has  treated  Canadian  students ;  though  we  came  to 

1  A  few  changes  have  been  made. 
vii 


PEEFACE 

her  as  strangers,  she  admitted  us  ungrudgingly  to  the  use  of  her  wide 
resources,  and  by  a  hospitality  more  generous  than  can  be  told  in 
words  bound  to  herself  our  hearts.  I  can  scarcely  record  here  the 
names  of  all  those  who  at  Harvard,  whether  by  mastery  in  the  things 
of  the  mind,  or  by  personal  kindness,  placed  me  in  their  debt;  but 
those  who  have  a  better  right  than  I  can  perhaps  allow  me  to  refer 
with  a  gratitude  made  deeper  by  the  sense  of  loss,  to  the  gifted  lady 
who  left  all  the  world  of  New  England  poorer  when  she  was  taken 
in  sudden  death  from  the  place  at  the  side  of  Professor  Palmer  which 
she  filled  with  such  grace  and  power. 

I  am  deeply  indebted  also  to  several  of  those  who  in  old-world 
universities  are  carrying  forward  the  greater  traditions  of  philosophy ; 
nor  is  my  sense  of  obligation  lessened  by  the  fact  that  they  would 
disapprove  of  many  things  in  these  pages.  The  thoughtfulness  of 
Professor  Kiilpe,  and  the  charm  of  his  grave  sincerity,  brightened  for 
me  a  time  at  Wiirzburg  when  work  was  almost  out  of  question. 
To  the  kindness  of  the  Master  of  Balliol  I  must  refer  with  the  special 
reverence  and  gratitude  due  to  one  whose  venerable  primacy  in 
philosophy  among  English-speaking  men  makes  him  "  our  father  Par- 
menides."  And  I  must  mention  one  other  name :  that  of  the  late 
Thomas  Hill  Green,  whose  living  voice  I  had  never  the  happiness  to 
hear,  but  whose  Prolegomena  to  Ethics — since  Cudworth's  day  the 
greatest  single  piece  of  constructive  work  in  the  British  literature 
of  metaphysic  and  ethics — was  my  "  introduction "  to  the  study  of 
philosophy. 

But  the  masters  in  the  schools  of  philosophy  will  find  no  fault 
with  me,  if  with  the  deepest  gratitude  of  all  I  mention  an  influence 
other  than  their  own,  though  not  alien  to  it — that  of  three  men  who 
live  now  in  God:  Lesslie  Matthew  Sweetnam,  who  bore  without 
flinching  a  fiery  trial  of  pain,  and  went  early  to  death,  giving  his 
own  life  in  the  attempt  to  save  by  operation  that  of  a  helpless  stranger 
—being  in  his  death  what  he  had  been  in  life,  a  prince  among  the 
surgeons  of  his  day,  and  a  man  whose  character  was  a  magnificence 
of  the  spirit ;  John  Petch,  sometime  Professor  of  French  in  Victoria 
College,  Toronto,  who  throughout  the  long  and  painful  illness  which 
preceded  his  death,  showed  to  those  who  waited  upon  him  the  same 

viii 


PBEFACE 

affectionate  consideration  and  gentle  courtesy  that  (joined  with  the 
finest  sense  of  honour)  had  become  in  the  days  of  his  strength  the 
settled  habit  of  his  mind;  and  my  father,  a  brave  and  gifted  man, 
who  endured  wrong  in  silence,  and  in  spite  of  a  frail  body  and  the 
cruelty  of  circumstance  discharged  with  fidelity  the  greater  human 
duties,  and  to  whom  at  last  there  came  gently  the  grace  of  sudden 
death.  To  these  three  men,  who  were  strong  enough  not  to  play  the 
rebel's  part  when  their  doom  was  hard,  but  had  their  hope  in  God, 
and  did  with  their  might  their  work  upon  the  earth,  the  pages  which 
follow  are  inscribed;  and  it  is  the  writer's  grief  that  to  their  dear 
and  lamented  names  he  is  not  able  to  erect  a  more  worthy  monument. 


VICTORIA  COLLEGE, 

TORONTO,  January,  1907. 


IX 


CONTENTS. 


PAGE 

INTRODUCTORY  1 

THE  STUDY  OF  NATURE  AND  THE  VISION  OP  GOD  15 

THE  METAPHYSIC  OF  SPINOZA  111 

PLATO  AND  THE  FOUNDING  OF  IDEALISM  201 

THE  COMPLETING  OF  IDEALISM     -  249 

ERIGENA  :  THE  DIVISION  OF  NATURE   -  269 

Erigena's  general  position  271 — 280 

The  four  Forms  of  Nature  280—331 

The  first  Form  281—282 

The  procession  from  the  first  Form  to  the  second     -  282 — 298 

The  procession  from  the  second  Form  to   the  third  298 — 310 

The  return  of  all  things— the  fourth  Form  of  Nature  310—331 

THE  THEISM  OF  ST.  THOMAS  333 

CONCLUSION  -  -       349 


INTRODUCTORY 

WHEN  some  great  Christian  kingdom  has  along  its  borders  no 
rest  from  war,  many  young  citizens — the  lion  being  still  supreme  in 
them1 — can  recognise  but  one  service  of  the  state.  The  watch  upon 
the  frontier,  with  its  discipline  of  arms  and  its  incessant  energies  of 
defense  and  attack,  is  to  them  at  once  the  duty  of  a  man  and  the 
meaning  of  citizenship  and  the  ideal  life.  But  the  years  bring  a 
graver  wisdom;  the  man  who  went  out  eagerly  to  the  tented 
field — if  he  has  retained  the  clear  sense  of  devotion  to  the  state, 
and  has  not  become  merely  subdued  to  the  trade  of  war — comes 
more  and  more  to  see  that,  great  as  is  his  present  service  to  the  state, 
there  is  another,  quieter  and  greater.  The  ultimate  strength  of  the 
state  lies  otherwhere:  in  patient  processes  and  structures  of  industry 
and  commerce  and  legislation ;  in  unnumbered  school-rooms ;  in  those 
ancient  houses  where  learning  is  cherished  for  its  own  sake,  and  for 
their  own  sake  the  sciences  are  cultivated,  and  out  of  piety  the  memory 
of  far-off  benefactors  is  kept  alive ;  above  all,  in  the  "  relations  dear  " 
of  the  homes,  with  their  "  charities  of  father,  son,  and  brother,"  and 
their  establishment  in  uprightness  and  integrity  of  the  characters  of 
those  who  presently  are  to  do  the  world's  work  and  shape  the  world's 
life;  and  in  those  companions  of  the  homes,  without  which  homes 
are  scarcely  homes  at  all,  the  parish  churches  that  with  sacraments 
and  holy  observances  and  the  making  of  habitual  prayer  lie  close  to 
our  mortal  life  from  its  beginning  to  its  close: — parish  churches 
where  the  vows  of  baptism  are  made  for  little  children;  and  with 
Morning  Prayer  and  Evensong  the  growing  life  is  reminded  day  by 
day  of  the  heavenly  glory  which  is  its  end;  and  to  each  relationship 
of  life,  with  all  that  is  in  it  of  labour  or  sacred  promise  or  discipline 
of  grief,  there  is  brought  by  solemn  offices  the  assistance  of  the 
heavenly  grace;  and  all,  at  last,  the  young  with  the  old,  the  poor 
side  by  side  with  the  great,  lay  themselves  down  together  to  their  sleep 

i  Plato,  Republic,  588. 
2  1 


INTRODUCTORY 

in  the  shadow  of  the  ancient  walls.  In  these  things  is  the  strength 
and  true  life  of  the  state;  nay,  these  things  are  the  state;  and  to 
them  the  man  upon  the  frontier — if  he  is  a  man  indeed,  and  the  times 
are  not  too  grim— makes  soon  or  late  his  way,  leaving  the  vigil  upon 
the  border  to  the  younger  men  with  whom  the  inward  and  spiritual 
voices  of  the  rational  soul  have  not  yet  come  to  mastery  and  the  call 
of  the  trumpet  remains  the  one  voice  of  duty. 

In  our  day  there  has  been  something  similar  to  this  in  the  com 
monwealth  of  philosophy.  It  too  has  had  its  border-warfare:  the 
strife  between  those  who  had,  and  those  who  had  not,  grasped  the 
ancient  and  cardinal  insight  of  philosophy,  that  if  you  would  under 
stand  the  nature  of  the  world  you  must  understand  the  relation  of  the 
world  to  the  soul.  That  insight  received  its  first  systematic  applica 
tion,  in  a  form  singularly  impressive  and  splendid,  from  Plato.  And 
to  win  it  again  and  learn  how  to  carry  it  once  more  to  its  systematic 
application,  has  been  precisely  the  work  of  recent  philosophy ;  a  work 
undertaken  upon  the  impulse  and  suggestion  of  Immanuel  Kant. 
Kant  compelled  us  to  see  that  in  any  attempt  to  form  a  view  of  the 
world  we  must  remember  from  the  beginning  that  the  facts  of  the 
world — all  facts  that  any  man  of  science  can  in  any  sense  inves 
tigate — are  facts  for  self-consciousness.  To  say  that  anything  is 
capable  of  undergoing  scientific  investigation  is  to  say  that  it  is 
capable  of  becoming  present  to,  of  being  comprehended  by,  of  having 
its  nature  and  structure  expressed  in  forms  of,  the  self-conscious  spirit 
which  is  man.  To  say  that  material  objects  can  be  known  is  to  say 
that  material  objects  are  capable  of  entering  into  organic  union  with 
self-conscious  intelligence.  Indeed,  it  is  not  doing  justice  to  the 
facts  of  the  case  to  say  merely  that  in  knowledge  there  is  a  union  of 
subject  and  object.  Throughout  the  whole  process  of  gaining  knowl 
edge  the  mind  itself  is  active;  active  in  shaping  the  impressions 
which  are  given  to  us  into  that  objective  order  of  facts  in  which  we 
live  and  which  we  call  the  world.  So  that  the  subject  actually  bears 
a  part  in  constructing  its  own  object  and  its  own  objective  order. 
Hence,  until  you  have  studied  that  activity  of  mind,  you  do  not  under 
stand  how  your  world  has  come  to  be  what  it  is;  you  do  not  under- 

2 


INTRODUCTORY 

stand  the  nature  and  structure  of  the  world  of  your  actual  life.  To 
try  to  understand  the  nature  of  the  world  without  reference  to  the 
activity  of  the  self-conscious  subject,  is  like  trying  to  solve  a  problem 
in  neglect  of  .its  central  factor  or  to  pronounce  final  verdict  upon  a 
case  in  forgetfulness  of  the  most  immediately  relevant  part  of  the 
evidence.  Nothing,  that  is  to  say,  worthy  of  being  called  a  scientific 
view  of  the  world — in  technical  terms,  nothing  worthy  of  being  called 
a  metaphysic — is  possible  to  a  man  until  he  considers  the  relation  of 
subject  and  object;  or,  to  state  the  case  more  narrowly,  until  he 
considers  the  fact  of  knowledge  and  raises  the  question  of  the  possi 
bility  of  knowledge.1 

But  in  the  age  immediately  preceding  our  own,  philosophy  found 

i  The  statement,  in  the  above  paragraph,  of  the  character  of  our  experience,  is  simply 
a  statement  of  fact.  It  is  not  metaphysic ;  but  it  clears  the  ground  for  metaphysic,  by 
describing  the  object  with  which  the  metaphysician  begins,  and  the  conditions  of  whose 
possibility  he  seeks  to  understand. 

In  our  own  day,  this  clearing  of  the  ground  for  metaphysical  construction  has  been 
effected  by  the  psychologists  in  a  way  more  primary— if  such  an  expression  may  be 
allowed— than  was  possible  to  Kant,  moving  painfully  as  he  did  under  his  accumulation 
of  inherited  burdens.  For  the  psychologist,  as  he  goes  on  with  his  analysis,  never  comes 
to  any  object  other  than  the  psychical  object ;  in  other  words,  the  realities  of  individual 
experience  are  always  psychical  realities.  Hence,  any  one  who  passes  from  psychology  to 
metaphysic  is  at  once  in  position  to  argue  that,  since  the  process  to  be  explained  is 
altogether  psychical,  that  which  explains  its  possibility  must  likewise  be  psychical ;  and 
this,  in  whichever  way  the  individual  experience  is  supposed  to  be  related  to  the  greater 
(or  total)  reality  whose  nature  the  metaphysician  seeks  to  know— whether  as  effect  to 
cause,  or  as  part  to  whole,  or  as  a  product  or  reproduction  to  a  source  whose  relation  to 
the  product  is  not  adequately  expressed  by  the  category  of  cause  and  effect. 

The  psychologist,  as  such,  has,  of  course,  no  concern  about  metaphysic  at  all.  His 
business  is  simply  to  observe  the  facts  and  processes  of  individual  experience  as  these 
actually  are.  But  if  he  performs  that  task  with  accuracy,  his  work— whether  he  intends 
it  or  no— clears  the  ground  for  metaphysical  construction  as  it  never  has  been  cleared 
before ;  and  this  puts  every  department  of  philosophy  under  a  great  debt  to  him.— In 
referring  to  this  contribution  of  the  psychologist  to  metaphysic,  I  am  thinking,  of  course, 
not  of  the  older  psychology — which  was  a  mixture  of  metaphysic  and  psychological 
observation  in  which  neither  component  came  to  its  right — but  of  the  psychology  which 
is  psychology  and  nothing  else  ;  the  psychology  which,  in  the  logical  order  of  the  sciences, 
is  the  first  of  the  sciences  of  observation.  This  is  often  called  the  "  new,"  or  "  experi 
mental,"  psychology.  But  the  adjectives  are  not  needed.  When  the  psychologist  applies 
methods  of  exact  measurement  to  such  psychical  phenomena  as  admit  of  exact  measure 
ment,  he  is  doing  only  what  any  man  of  science  ought  to  do.  The  fact  that  certain 
elements  and  certain  processes  in  our  experience  admit  of  fairly  exact  measurement,  does 
not  make  experience  and  the  experienced  world  any  the  less  spiritual  or  any  the  more 
mechanical.— In  this  connexion  I  should  refer,  with  warm  admiration,  to  the  name  of 
Professor  Kirschmann  of  the  University  of  Toronto.  I  do  this,  not  as  in  any  sense  sug 
gesting  that  Professor  Kirschmann  would  approve  of  the  views  expressed  in  these  pages  ; 
but  as  indicating  my  own  gratitude  to  him  and  to  his  teaching. 

3 


INTRODUCTORY 

itself  face  to  face  with  views  of  the  world  which  were  formed  by 
absolutely  the  opposite  procedure  and  yet  were  threatening  to  dom 
inate  the  world.  For  there  are  more  metaphysicians  in  the  world 
than  the  Platonists  and  the  Kantians.  All  men  are  metaphysicians 
by  nature ;  and  most  men  impatient  and  hasty  metaphysicians.  They 
rush  into  metaphysic  from  whatever  scientific  ground  they  happen 
to  have  been  working  upon,  and  construct  metaphysical  systems  with 
whatever  categories  they  have  been  accustomed  to  use,  without  con 
sidering  that  there  is  an  intervening  question — this  question  of  the 
possibility  of  knowledge,  and  of  the  relation  of  the  categories  to 
nature.  The  physicist,  for  example,  when  he  obeys  the  human 
impulse  to  be  metaphysical,  is  tempted  simply  to  treat  the  physical 
point  of  view  as  the  ultimate  one,  and  the  categories  of  physical 
science  as  the  ultimate  categories — the  ultimate  principles  of  explana 
tion  of  the  world.  Without  quite  seeing  what  he  is  doing — for  since 
he  scorns  the  word  "  metaphysic,"  it  is  easy  for  him  to  imagine  that 
he  also  scorns  the  thing — he  gets  a  metaphysic  of  his  own  at  one 
stroke,  by  simply  taking  his  physics  as  metaphysic.  That  the  facts 
of  our  experience  have  relations  other  than  the  physical;  that  an 
investigation  of  these  might  lead  to  a  deeper  knowledge  of  the  facts, 
and  even  to  a  re-interpretation  of  the  physical  relations  themselves; 
that  there  is  an  inquiry  (epistemology)  which  seeks  to  conduct  pre 
cisely  this  investigation: — this  he  does  not  see,  and,  not  seeing  it, 
enters  boldly  and  easily  upon  a  world-view  which  is  blind  to  all 
aspects  of  the  world  but  one ;  and  so  we  get  that  hasty  and  premature 
metaphysic  which,  when  it  puts  the  emphasis  at  one  point,  is  called 
Materialism;  when  at  another  point,  the  mechanical  view  of  the 
world.  Then  come  other  men  of  science  who  see  that  materialistic 
and  mechanical  views  are  not  adequate  as  explanations  of  the  world 
of  our  experience,  but  who  yet  will  have  nothing  to  do  with  the 
epistemological  problem;  these,  finding  the  way  of  advance  barred 
to  themselves,  assert  that  it  is  barred  to  all  men;  and  thus  we  get 
the  final  development  of  this  type  of  metaphysic,  the  development 
seen  in  the  various  forms  of  Agnosticism.1 

i  The  Agnosticism  here  meant  is  that  which  may  be  called  Agnosticism  for  its  own 
sake;  not  that  which,  in  ancient  and  mediaeval  times,  was  simply  one  of  the  momenta 
of  Mysticism. 

4 


INTKODUCTOKY 

These  types  of  metaphysic  have  in  our  day  exercised  an  immense 
influence.  In  the  first  place  they  have  been  powerful  through  a  sort 
of  transferred  glory :  the  men  who  have  urged  them  upon  us  are  in 
many  ways  our  benefactors ;  are  members  of  that  great  host  to  whose 
untiring  labour  and  magnificent  achievement  in  physical  and  natural 
science  we  are  all  of  us — and  none  of  us  more  than  the  theologians — 
profoundly  indebted.  And  in  the  second  place  their  influence  has 
been  wide  because  the  movement  of  thought  already  described,  the 
movement  of  thought  by  which  one  drifts  into  them  from  the  modern 
scientific  consciousness,  is  so  easy  and  so  natural.  Certain  principles 
of  explanation  used  upon  certain  aspects  of  reality  prove  splendidly 
successful;  what  more  easy  than  to  take  for  granted  that  these  are 
the  supreme  principles  in  the  whole  arsenal  of  man's  mind?  And 
that  view  once  taken,  the  conclusions  follow  directly :  either  you  apply 
these  principles  to  the  explanation  of  the  whole  process  of  the  universe, 
and  so  gain  a  materialistic  or  mechanical  view  of  the  world;  or  you 
see  that  there  are  facts  which  these  principles  cannot  explain,  and  then 
you  say  that,  since  these  principles  are  the  supreme  principles  of 
science,  those  facts  are  incapable  of  scientific  explanation  and  lie 
beyond  the  horizon  of  human  knowledge  altogether.  But,  however 
easy  such  a  movement  of  thought  be,  or  however  attractive  to  human 
nature,  the  present-day  student  of  philosophy  who  knows  his  own 
field — which  amounts  to  saying,  who  has  entered  into  metaphysic  by 
the  gateway  of  epistemology — has  no  choice  but  to  insist  that  views 
formed  in  this  way  are  premature,  uncritical,  dogmatic;  they 
announce  their  conclusions  without  having  investigated  a  great  prob 
lem  which  is  not  merely  relevant  but  fundamental. 

That  is  to  say,  to  return  to  the  comparison  of  a  moment  ago,  such 
a  student  recognises  in  views  of  this  sort  the  hostile  encampments 
upon  the  frontier;  barbarians  having  nature's  own  strength  in  them 
and  therefore  magnificent  in  intellectual  and  spiritual  potentialities, 
but  seeking  to  destroy  the  ancient  civilisation  of  church  and  state 
in  which  alone  can  the  nature  in  them  or  in  any  man  come  to  its  true 
fulfilment.  And  while  he  is  still  young  he  is  likely  to  feel  it  his 
special  vocation  to  take  up  the  conflict  with  these;  always  he  is 
devising  some  new  and  clearer  statement  of  Platonic  or  Kantian 

5 


INTRODUCTORY 

epistemology,  such  as  will  set  out  in  plain  light  the  immense  and  yet 
rudimentary  fallacy  of  which  they  are  habitually  guilty,  and  without 
which  their  systems  and  their  outlook  upon  the  world  would  never 
have  come  into  being  at  all.  But  as  he  grows  older  he  finds  that  he 
himself  has  something  to  learn;  riot  a  new  lesson  exactly,  but  a  new 
temper.  To  him  as  well  as  to  others  that  graver  wisdom  of  the  years 
is  brought ;  his  heart  begins  to  apprehend,  and  to  respond  to,  a  greater 
call.  If  his  vocation  is  to  be  fulfilled  in  its  integrity,  he  must  pass 
on  to  those  constructive  labours  that  regard  nothing  save  truth  in  her 
eternal  form.  And  to  take  part  in  such  labours  there  is  but  one  way : 
he  must  turn  to  the  ancient  and  catholic  homes  of  his  great  science, 
must  make  them  the  dwelling-place  of  his  mind,  in  their  faith  and 
in  the  power  of  their  still  light  must  at  once  look  upon  and  participate 
in  the  struggle  and  fate  of  man.  It  is  necessary,  indeed,  that  the 
controversy  upon  the  marches  be  maintained.  But  that  work  of  serv 
ing  God  with  the  sword  he  may  well  leave  to  younger  men.  In  the 
kingdom  of  the  intellect,  the  greater  service  of  God  is  that  of  those 
who  in  peaceful  labour  draw  nearest  to  His  glory ;  and  so,  for  himself, 
in  the  years  that  are  left,  he  will  turn  toward  that  central  region 
where,  in  their  own  native  and  appropriate  forms,  the  greater  things 
of  philosophy  stand  in  peace,  and  the  spirits  of  the  masters  abide  in 
the  temples  which  they  themselves  have  built.  There  he  will  dwell, 
and  will  seek,  so  far  as  he  can,  both  to  live  over  again  in  himself  the 
great  histories  which  have  been  enacted  there,  and  to  keep  the  access 
to  those  homes  of  light  open  to  whatever  men  may  be  led  by  trouble 
of  mind  or  by  an  inner  vocation  to  turn  their  faces  that  way. 

But  this  central  and  catholic  region  of  philosophy — what  is  it 
like  ?  In  a  moment  we  shall  have  to  consider  the  great  division  which 
is  found  in  it.  But  first  we  must  note  the  distinguishing  characters 
in  which  all  its  structures  and  labours  share,  and  which  make  it,  with 
all  its  divisions,  still  one  realm.  These  characters  are,  in  the  main, 
two;  two  characters  which  may  seem  very  broad,  very  fugitive,  very 
impalpable,  to  the  man  who  looks  upon  the  matter  from  the  outside; 
but  the  opposite  of  fugitive  or  impalpable  to  the  man  who  looks  out 
upon  philosophy  from  its  own  central  point  of  view.  In  the  first 

G 


INTEODUCTOEY 

place,  the  philosophies  which  belong  here,  however  radically  they  differ 
from  one  another  in  other  respects,  agree  in  this — they  are  a  wisdom 
of  the  soul.  They  remember  that  reality  is  the  seat  and  home  of  the 
soul,  and  that,  therefore,  in  forgetfulness  of  the  soul  reality  can  never 
be  understood  or  rightly  interpreted.  In  the  second  place,  they  agree 
also  in  this,  that  to  them  truth  and  life  are  one.  With  whatever 
differences  among  themselves,  they  constitute  that  greater  philosophy 
which,  at  one  and  the  same  time  and  by  one  and  the  same  impulse, 
seeks  to  know  reality  and  to  enter  into  union  with  it.  On  the  one 
side,  such  philosophy  is  what  the  Germans  call  Wissenschaft,  what 
Plato  and  Aristotle  with  a  still  severer  exaltation  of  meaning  called 
eniGTrj^rf,  and  what  in  these  pages  (contrary  to  the  ordinary  usage 
of  English  men  of  thought)  will  be  called  science.  On  this  side, 
seeking  knowledge  for  the  sake  of  knowledge,  it  endeavours  to  com 
prehend  intellectually  the  world  of  which  it  is  itself  a  part.  But  the 
same  impulse  and  the  same  passion  has  as  its  other  side  the  endeavour 
to  be  at  one  with  the  reality  which  it  has  scientifically  apprehended. 
It  seeks  to  take,  as  its  way,  the  way  of  that  reality;  seeks  to  take  the 
nature  of  that  reality  as  its  guide,  the  law  and  informing  spirit  of  that 
reality  as  its  law  and  its  spirit.  And  so  it  is  a  principle  of  the  unity 
of  life;  it  seeks  the  unity  of  life  by  seeking  that  union  with  ultimate 
reality  in  which  science  and  religion  are  one. 

But,  as  already  has  been  indicated,  within  the  limits  of  the  greater 
philosophy  which  has  these  distinguishing  characters,  there  is  a  cer 
tain  profound  and  thoroughgoing  division.  In  the  attempt  to  appre 
hend  the  true  nature  of  reality,  and  consequently  in  the  endeavour 
to  bring  the  life  of  man  into  accord  with  reality,  there  have  been 
two  great  methods,  two  great  tendencies,  the  distinction  between 
which  is  not  broken  down  by  the  fact  that  historically  they  have 
entered  into  the  most  manifold  relations  of  combination  and  of  con 
flict  with  each  other.  The  division  arises,  as  all  great  human 
divisions  arise,  from  the  existence  of  divergent  tendencies  in  human 
nature  itself,  and  of  radical  differences  in  the  experience,  happy  or 
tragic,  which  falls  to  the  lot  of  individuals  and  races.  And  since  it 
arises  in  the  effort  to  apprehend  ultimate  reality,  it  is  a  division 
elemental  and  ultimate — the  most  radical  of  all  the  divisions  known 

7 


INTEODUCTOEY 

to  human  nature  and  human  life,  and  the  one  that  must  always  be 
kept  in  mind,  as  a  sort  of  ground-plan,  in  any  attempt  to  understand 
the  spiritual  history  of  man.  The  tendencies  themselves,  however, 
and  the  two  types  of  philosophy  to  which  they  give  rise,  we  must  seek 
to  understand  somewhat  more  fully. 

Each  of  the  two  types  of  philosophy  is  a  movement  from  the 
changing  and  transient  facts  of  the  experienced  world  to  a  principle 
which  is  one  and  eternal;  or,  as  this  would  usually  be  expressed,  is 
a  movement  from  the  world  to  God.  But  each  makes  that  movement 
in  its  own  way.  The  one,  in  moving  from  the  world  to  God,  does  not 
forget  the  world  from  which  it  started.  When  it  finds  the  explanation 
of  the  world  in  a  vision  of  God,  it  returns  to  the  world,  and  seeks  to 
give  to  the  facts  of  the  world  their  true  interpretation  in  the  light 
of  that  vision  of  God.  The  facts  of  the  world  and  of  our  life  are  to 
it  elements  in  a  divine  plan,  the  history  of  the  world  a  process  in 
which  an  eternal  purpose  is  being  realised.  The  nature  of  God — 
and  therefore,  however  veiled  by  cloud  and  storm,  the  nature  of  the 
world — is  that  for  which  human  language  has  no  single  word,1  but 
which  may  be  expressed  by  putting  together  the  three  words,  reason, 
righteousness,  love.  And  in  unity  with  that  true  or  ultimate  nature 
of  the  universe  lies  the  way  of  life  for  man;  in  character,  unity  with 
the  divine  character ;  in  action,  unity  with  the  divine  purpose.  Since, 
furthermore,  the  purpose  of  God  is  the  ultimate  law  of  the  world, 
since  the  plan  of  God  realises  itself  in  and  through  the  history  of  the 
world,  that  character  and  action  in  which  man  seeks  to  become  at  one 
with  God  must  be  character  and  action  in  this  present  world,  not  out 
of  it.  It  is  in  and  through  the  ways  of  this  present  life,  in  and 
through  the  "  daily  round  "  and  the  "  common  task/'  in  and  through 
the  regular  forms  and  relationships,  the  normal  duties  and  affections, 
of  human  work  and  human  homes,  that  a  man  must  make  himself  at 
one  with  the  eternal  reality.  Even  as  there  is  "no  other  genuine 
enthusiasm  for  humanity,"  so  also,  to  extend  the  late  Professor 
Green's  well-known  statement,  there  is  on  this  view  no  other  genuine 
enthusiasm  for  God  and  for  the  eternal,  than  one  "which  has 
travelled  the  common  highway  of  reason — the  life  of  the  good  neigh- 

1  Unless  it  be  the  word  "spirit,"  in  its  concrete  sense. 
8 


INTBODUCTOKY 

bour  and  the  honest  citizen — and  can  never  forget  that  it  is  still  only 
a  further  stage  of  the  same  journey." 

The  other  tendency  follows  just  the  opposite  procedure.  In 
moving  toward  God  it  leaves  the  world  behind.  For  the  reality, 
knowledge  of  which  is  truth,  and  union  with  which  is  the  way  of 
life — is  it  not  something  essentially  different  from  these  present 
appearances  ? — if  not,  why  are  we  dissatisfied  with  these  appearances  ? 
What,  indeed,  sets  us  at  all  upon  that  quest  which,  as  thinking,  is 
philosophy,  but  as  a  life  is  religion,  save  precisely  this,  that  the 
appearances  which  constitute  our  present  experience  and  our  present 
world  are  profoundly  unsatisfactory?  They  are  transient — they  fleet 
away  and  leave  life  empty  for  the  man  that  trusted  in  them. 
Logically,  they  are  self-contradictory.  Morally  and  religiously  they 
are  inadequate,  if  indeed  they  do  not  stand  absolutely  condemned. 
Then  how  shall  we  define  reality  save  by  denying  of  it  the  characters 
of  the  appearances  which  make  up  our  experience?  And  so  reality 
comes  to  be  conceived,  not  as  that  which  at  once  explains  and  con 
tains  the  things  and  forms  of  our  present  life,  the  home  of  them  and 
the  truth  of  them,  their  law  and  their  informing  spirit,  but  as  some 
thing  which  exists  purely  in  itself  and  cannot  be  given  to  us  under 
the  ordinary  forms  of  our  thinking.  On  the  contrary,  it  can  be 
described  only  by  denying  of  it  all  the  characteristics  of  what  can  be 
so  given  to  us.  It  is  true  that  the  men  who  seek  reality  by  this 
method  usually  have,  explicitly  or  implicitly,  formal  definitions  of  it — 
definitions  of  which  the  ancient  and  ever-recurring  one,  that  "  sub 
stance  is  that  which  for  its  existence  stands  in  need  of  nothing  but 
itself,"  is  a  type.  But  no  positive  or  concrete  characterisation  is 
possible — when  reality  is  described  as  one,  eternal,  unchangeable, 
these  are  not  so  much  positive  characters  as  negations  of  the  multi 
plicity,  the  diversity,  the  change  and  transience,  of  that  which  is  given 
to  us  and  is  our  experience.  For,  as  we  have  just  seen,  the  very 
method  by  which  the  real  is  sought  to  be  reached  makes  impossible 
any  attempt  to  tell  what  its  positive  content  or  nature  is.  The  forms, 
the  energies,  the  activities,  which  are  manifest  in  our  experience, 
and  make  our  world  what  it  is — what  you  know  about  reality  is  that 
it  is  not  these.  There  is  a  reality,  indeed — that  is  your  first  and 

9 


INTRODUCTORY 

profoundest  conviction  as  a  denier  of  this  false  world  in  the  name  of 
the  truly  real;1  and  that  reality  needs  for  its  existence  nothing  save 
itself ;  but  you  are  sure  that  it/  as  it  is  in  itself,  is  never  given  to  you, 
and  cannot  be  given  to  you,  under  the  ordinary  form  of  your 
experience.  And  so,  in  your  search  for  reality,  you  must  say  of  any 
natural  or  intellectual  or  moral  form  known  to  man's  present 
experience,  "  It  is  not  that." 

In  a  word,  this  philosophy,  when  it  has  gained  its  goal  and  its 
rest  in  God,  remembers  the  world  no  more,  except  as  a  dream  and 
an  illusion  which,  at  the  coming  of  the  vision  of  God,  has  vanished 
back  into  its  own  native  and  original  nothingness.  Reality  is  that 
which  the  world  of  our  experience  is  not.  And  as  reality  is  conceived, 
so  also  is  the  true  way  of  life  conceived.  All  that  you  can  say  of  the 
consciousness  or  experience  which  is  at  one  with  reality,  is  that  it  is 
not  our  present  consciousness;  that  it  has  no  kinship  in  form  or 
procedure  with  the  normal  consciousness  manifest  in  man's  ordinary 
science  and  labour,  religion  and  society;  that  even  such  terms  as 
"  consciousness "  or  "  experience "  can  be  applied  to  it  only  by 
accommodation. 

Of  all  the  divisions  or  distinctions  that  are  found  in  human 
experience  and  have  been  influential  in  shaping  the  world's  history, 
this  is — in  the  sense  of  being  first  and  elemental — the  most  important. 
Its  fullest  and  most  concrete  expression  of  itself  has  been,  of  course, 
in  religion.  On  the  one  side  stand  religions  like  Brahmanism  (and, 
in  a  modified  sense,  Buddhism) — the  religion  of  men  who  deny  the 
world  and  seek  to  become  one  with  a  reality  which  is  not  the  changing 
world;2  on  the  other,  religions  like  Christianity,  which  see  that  it  is 
only  in  God  and  unto  God  that  the  world  reaches  its  truth  and  reality. 
Indeed,  if  one  were  speaking  of  Christendom — still  more,  if  one  were 
speaking  of  the  church — rather  than  of  Christianity,  one  would  have 
to  say  that  its  history  is  a  history  precisely  of  the  conflict  of  these 
two  tendencies  within  one  body.  And  naturally,  as  to  some  extent 

1  Though  you  may  feel  compelled  to  object  to  all  possible  human  ways  of  expressing 
that  conviction. 

2  "You  let  your  boat  drop  quietly  down  the  Ganges  to-day,  and  along  its  banks  the 
silent  figures  sit  like  carved  brown  statues,  hour  after  hour,  day  after  day,  with  eyes  open 
and  fixed  on  vacancy,  clearing  themselves  of  all  thought,  emotion,  and  desire,  that,  being 
emptied  of  self,  they  may  see  God."— [I  cannot  find  the  reference.] 

10 


INTRODUCTORY 

we  have  seen  already,  this  deepest  distinction  in  man's  practical  life 
has  expressed  itself  also,  in  every  age  and  in  numberless  ways,  in 
his  endeavour  rationally  to  comprehend  himself  and  his  life,  whether 
that  attempt  be  called  philosophy  or  theology.  Indeed,  the  man  who 
attempts  to  understand  the  history  of  philosophy,  or  of  theology  (in 
the  ancient  sense  of  the  term),  without  understanding  this  distinction 
and  its  place  in  those  histories,  is  like  a  man  of  science  who  should 
examine  the  surface  of  some  great  current,  without  penetrating  to  the 
forces  that  actually  have  determined  and  actually  are  determining 
its  nature  and  its  flow. 

Of  these  two  great  types  of  religion,  of  theology,  of  philosophy, 
the  one  which,  in  seeking  its  home  in  God,  follows  in  the  way  just 
indicated  the  via  negativa,  is  commonly  called  Mysticism.  To  it  the 
nature  of  God  is  altogether  beyond  the  categories  of  our  intelligence ; 
the  vision  of  God,  which  is  the  light  of  the  soul,  is  altogether  above 
the  ways  and  activities  of  our  understanding;  the  rest  in  God,  which 
is  the  blessedness  of  the  soul,  is  altogether  apart  from  the  ordinary 
forms  of  our  experience.  Hence  the  name  is  quite  appropriate.  The 
true,  the  real,  the  One, — words  cannot  utter  it  nor  thought  conceive 
it;  how,  then,  shall  the  man  who  seeks  it  describe  himself  to  the 
ordinary  intelligence?  and  how  shall  the  ordinary  intelligence  express 
its  judgment  concerning  him  ?  Obviously  there  is  but  one  way.  He, 
whether  as  he  attempts  to  describe  himself  to  it,  or  as  it  judges  him, 
is  a  Mystic;  and  his  way  of  life  is  Mysticism.  The  other  tendency, 
when  formulated  as  a  philosophy,  is  known  historically  as  Idealism. 
Its  first  world-historical  master  was  Plato;  from  one  of  his  great 
words  the  name  itself  is  taken.  As  a  view  of  the  world,  it  was  in 
part  explicitly  wrought  out  by  him,  in  part  made  possible  by  him  to 
later  men  of  thought  who  worked,  on  the  one  hand,  with  more 
powerful  categories  and  therefore  with  greater  opportunities  for  self- 
consistency,  but  on  the  other  hand  with  less  of  inspiration,  less  of 
political  and  moral  and  religious  passion.  But  Idealism,  in  this 
greater  sense  of  the  name,1  the  modern  world  has  had  almost  to 
conquer  anew  for  itself.  And  he  who  made  the  reconquest  possible, 

1  As  distinct  from  the  Sensationalism  of  the  English  School,  which  also,  because  it  is  a 
"  way  of  ideas  "  (in  the  sense  of  that  word  so  unhappily  used  hy  John  Locke)  has  been 
called  Idealism. 

11 


INTKODUCTOKY 

though  he  did  his  work  stumblingly  and  with  all  possible  awkward 
ness,  was  Immanuel  Kant. 

This,  then,  is  the  first  great  division — and  the  most  radical  of 
all  possible  divisions — within  the  "  church  catholic  "  of  philosophy. 
It  is  the.  extreme  and  complete  opposition  of  the  via  negativa  to  that 
positive  or  synthetic  method  which  insists  that  the  true  universal  is 
at  once  the  home  and  the  explanation  of  the  particulars,  and  which, 
therefore,  when  it  has  gained  a  vision  of  God,  seeks  to  use  that  vision 
as  the  light  which  gives  a  true  vision  of  the  world.  But  this  first 
division  is  not  all;  there  is  a  second  and  lesser  to  be  considered — one 
within  Idealism.  For  the  via  negativa,  where  it  does  not  secure  that 
full  triumph  which  (as  at  once  a  metaphysic  and  a  way  of  life)  is 
Mysticism,  is  sometimes  able  to  cross  over  into  the  field  of  its 
opponent  and  secure  a  partial  victory  there.  These  are  the  cases 
where  it  cannot  win  men  away  from  believing  that  the  forms  of  reason 
express  the  nature  of  reality — that  ultimate  reality  is  perfect  reason. 
But  it  does  lead  them  to  believe  that  you  must  separate  pure  reason 
from  sensation  and  sense-experience,  and  then  accept  that  pure  reason 
alone  as  expressing  the  nature  of  reality.  So  that  you  have  reality 
as  a  world  of  abstract  pure  reason,  and  pure  reason  in  man  appre 
hending  it;  and  then  you  somehow  have  another  world,  the  sense- 
world,  and  corresponding  to  it,  man's  sense-experience.  And  the  true 
way  of  life  is  to  renounce  this  lower  world  and  all  its  ways,  and  to 
live  only  in  that  upper  world. — This  way  of  thinking  may,  for  con 
venience  of  reference,  be  called  Abstract  Idealism ;  in  distinction  from 
it,  the  fully-developed  type  may  be  called  Concrete  Idealism — Hegel 
called  it  Absolute  Idealism. 

We  have,  then,  to  sum  up,  a  twofold  opposition  of  the  great  ten 
dencies  which  we  have  been  considering:  first,  their  extreme  oppo 
sition,  giving  us  Mysticism  and  Idealism;  secondly,  their  lesser 
opposition  within  the  field  of  Idealism,  giving  us  Abstract  and  Con 
crete  Idealism.1 

i  When  the  distinction  between  these  two  types  of  philosophy  and  of  religion  is  stated 
—and  not  only  stated,  but  insisted  upon— a  very  old  question  is  likely  to  recur  in  a  new 
form  :  Of  what  value  is  the  distinction  between  the  inner  kingdom  of  philosophy  and  its 
borderland  contentions,  if  that  inner  kingdom  itself  is  rent  apart  by  divisions  of  the  most 

12 


INTRODUCTORY 

It  is  with  this  central  and  catholic  region  of  philosophy,  and  with 
this  twofold  opposition  of  fundamental  tendencies  within  it,  that  the 
following  papers  are  in  the  main  concerned.  Most  of  them  were 
written  as  separate  studies;  a  fact  which  gives  to  each  its  own  angle 
of  approach,  and  involves,  also,  a  certain  amount  of  repetition.  But 
they  had  a  common  purpose;1  and  when  taken  together  have  still  a 
certain  unity  of  plan,  which  may  be  indicated  as  follows. — The  first 
two  essays  deal  with  the  main  antithesis  itself,  that  between  Idealism 
and  Mysticism: — the  first  outlining,  in  simple  form,  and  with  refer 
ence  to  the  life  of  our  own  day,  the  Idealistic  position;  while  the 
second,  in  the  historical  discussion  of  what  is  there  called  Spinoza's 
"first  metaphysic,"  traces  the  development  of  Mysticism.  The 
remaining  papers  are  studies  in  the  history  of  Idealism,  with  special 
reference  to  the  conflict  of  tendencies  just  described — the  lesser  con 
flict  within  Idealism,  the  greater  between  Idealism  and  Mysticism. 
The  history  is  studied,  not  consecutively,  but  by  turning  to  those 
great  masters  in  ancient  and  mediaeval  thought  in  whom  the  forces 
that  operate  throughout  the  whole  history  are  seen  working  with 
special  clearness  and  intensity.  In  Plato  is  seen,  for  instance,  the 

fundamental  kind?  The  doubt  implied  in  such  a  question  is,  however,  not  justified  ;  its 
unfairness  can  be  shown — if  it  is  allowable  to  ride  a  parable  so  hard — by  turning  once 
more  to  the  comparison  suggested  earlier  in  the  text.  In  the  country  there  spoken  of,  the 
observer  would  soon  have  become  aware  of  the  existence  of  political  parties.  And  as  he 
looked  upon  the  "fell  incensed  points  "  of  their  stubborn  opposition,  he  might  easily  be 
tenanted  to  say  that  the  division  between  these  parties  was  a  far  more  fundamental 
one  than  that  between  citizens  within  and  hardy  barbarians  without.  And  yet,  in  one 
most  important  respect,  he  would  be  wrong.  For,  no  matter  how  radical  the  opposition 
of  those  parties,  their  members  have  after  all  the  most  important  things  of  life  in  com 
mon  ;  they  have  a  common  speech,  a  common  literature,  common  arts  and  education,  a 
common  religion— in  one  word,  a  common  citizenship.  The  two  parties  are  kindred  to 
each  other  in  a  sense  in  which  neither  of  them  is  kindred  to  that  race  of  other  blood  that 
troubles  the  marches.  And  so  here.  Mysticism  and  Ide  ilism  are  certainly  as  far  apart 
as  any  types  of  philosophy  or  of  religion  can  possibly  be.  But  they  agree  in  this:  they 
know  that  the  quest  for  the  unity  of  existence  and  the  quest  for  the  true  end  and  home  of 
the  soul  are  one  and  the  same  quest.  Out  of  one  and  the  same  impulse  proceed  their 
effort  after  the  intellectual  apprehension  of  reality,  and  their  effort,  whether  by  ordinary 
or  extraordinary  experience,  after  the  union  of  the  soul  with  that  reality.— Of  course,  the 
other  side  of  the  matter  should  not  be  forgotten.  Barbarian  and  citizen,  though  without 
a  common  citizenship,  have  a  common  human  nature  ;  it  lies  within  the  potentialities  of 
the  barbarian's  soul  to  become  a  citizen.  So  too,  the  Materialist  or  the  Agnostic  need 
only  do  justice  to  himself,  and  to  the  intellectual  impulses  already  at  work  within  him, 
to  become  an  Idealist. 

i  See  Preface,  p.  vii. 

13 


INTRODUCTORY 

founding  of  Idealism  as  a  systematic  view  of  the  world  and  of  life. 
Then,  when  Greek  thought,  as  one  of  the  constituent  elements  of  the 
mind  of  the  church,  had  gone  out  into  the  wide  world,  the  strife,  or 
rather  the  combination,  of  Idealism  with  Mysticism  is  seen  in 
Erigena;  and  the  struggle  between  the  two  types  of  Idealism  in  St. 
Thomas. 


14 


THE  STUDY  OF  NATURE  AND   THE 
VISION  OF  GOD 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUBE    AND    THE 
VISION    OF   GOD. 


AMONG  the  leaders  of  the  English  people  in  the  nineteenth  century 
there  was  one  strangely  devoid  of  the  qualities  and  habits  that  we 
have  grown  accustomed  to  look  for  in  a  modern  leader  of  modern 
men,  and  strangely  out  of  accord  with  what  the  world  regards  as  the 
genius  of  England.  He  was  no  captain  of  industry.  He  was  the 
head  of  no  princely  merchant  house.  He  was  not  a  statesman;  not 
a  jurist;  not  one  of  the  proconsuls  of  England,  who  establish  her 
peace  abroad  in  seats  of  ancient  anarchy.  He  had  no  part  in  the 
labours  of  commerce,  of  war,  of  civil  administration,  by  which  Britain 
has  done  for  parts  of  the  modern  world  what  Eome,  with  more  con 
tinuous  but 'more  selfish  energies,  did  for  the  whole  of  the  ancient. 
From  all  these,  the  circles  in  which  the  leaders  of  England  habitually 
move  and  the  works  at  which  they  habitually  labour,  he  turned 
deliberately  and  resolutely  away.  He  made  no  quest  of  any  sort  after 
personal  popularity.  His  voice  was  not  heard  in  the  streets;  and 
when,  from  quiet  places  and  chosen  retreats,  he  spoke  to  the  people 
of  England,  it  was  with  warning  and  grave  rebuke.  Every  word 
revealed  a  great  gulf:  on  one  side  that  solitary  man;  on  the  other, 
the  customary  life,  the  habitual  thoughts,  the  characteristic  activities, 
of  his  race.  And  in  the  presence  of  that  gulf  there  came  to  Cardinal 
Newman's  lips  no  single  syllable  of  concession  or  of  compromise. 

Once,  indeed,  he  had  been  in  more  intimate  contact  with  English 
life  and  English  thought  and  English  institutions.  Virtually,  though 
not  in  name,  he  had  been  the  leader  of  the  chivalry  of  the  Church 
of  England  in  its  battle  with  modern  Liberalism ;  and  had  guided  the 
first  steps  of  that  ecclesiastical  revolution  which  has  exercised  upon  the 
life  of  the  great  body  of  Englishmen  an  influence  more  widely  form- 

3  17 


THE    STUDY    OF    JSTATUBE 

ative  than  they  themselves  know.  But  those  days  were  now  done. 
That  leadership  had  been  laid  aside,  and  for  ever.  He  had  with 
drawn  from  the  noises  of  the  world,  and  had  sat  him  down  in  the 
quiet  of  an  institution,  itself  in  its  very  nature  repugnant  to  the 
temper  of  England  and  alien  to  her  settled  thoughts.  It  seemed  as 
if  his  influence  upon  the  men  of  England  were  shattered  for  ever  and 
by  his  own  act.  But  what  really  came  to  pass  was  that  that  influence 
gradually  took  on  a  new  life.  It  became  more  impalpable,  less  obtru 
sive,  less  noticeable;  became  something  which  few  journalists  would 
have  remembered  in  enumerating  the  "  forces  of  the  day."  But  it 
became  profounder,  instinct  with  a  power  more  truly  essential  and 
therefore  more  abiding.  And  it  became  so,  because  it  became  more 
broadly  and  simply  human,  more  free  from  party  interests  and  party 
accidents,  more  deeply  rooted  in  the  elementary  material  of  life.  The 
change  in  the  character  of  the  influence  was  due  to  a  change  which 
had  come  to  the  man  himself  who  exercised  it.  A  great  division  had 
passed  out  of  his  life.  True,  there  were  still  difficulties  for  him. 
The  policy  of  the  Eoman  Curia  in  the  days  of  Pius  might  grieve  him 
deeply.  But  it  could  never  shatter  the  very  foundations  of  his  life, 
as  once  the  attitude  and  the  decisions  of  the  Anglican  bishops  had 
done.  In  spite  of  all  difficulties  the  fact  remained  that  the  much- 
tried  spirit  had  found  its  home.  Equably  and  strongly  it  moved 
henceforth  on  its  way,  like  some  star  which  at  its  true  altitude  and 
in  its  appointed  and  established  orbit  sweeps  steadily  forward  "  without  I 
haste  and  without  rest."  In  that  deep  assurance  of  soul  Newman ; 
turned,  as  was  natural,  more  and  more  to  the  things  that  are  truly  j 
catholic;  more  and  more  to  the  things  that  do  not  belong  to  parties 
and  do  not  pass  away  with  parties ;  more  and  more  to  the  things  that, 
being  eternal,  are,  in  the  words  used  a  moment  ago,  broadly  and 
simply  human.  It  is  true,  he  remained  an  uncompromising  advocate 
of  the  Eoman  view  of  the  church  and  the  Eoman  interpretation  of 
history.  But — though  he  himself  would  indignantly  have  repudiated 
the  distinction — his  influence  as  such  an  advocate  came  to  be  the  least 
important  part  of  his  influence;  his  deepest  power  upon  his  genera 
tion  was  not  that  which  he  exerted  as  a  prophet  of  the  specifically 
Eoman  ideal  in  its  conflict  with  the  spirit  of  the  time  and  with  the 

18 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

spirit  of  England.  His  true  significance  as  a  leader  and  benefactor 
of  the  English  race  came  more  and  more  to  lie,  not  in  any  party 
advocacy,  but  in  the  fact  that,  in  an  age  devoted  to  material  prosperity 
and  to  the  objects  and  interests  of  a  materialised  life,  he,  with  no 
particle  of  submission  to  the  spirit  of  the  age,  was  a  pilgrim  of  eternity 
and  a  prophet  of  eternity. 

And  this  came  to  be  recognised  by  the  men  of  clearest  eyes  in 
England;  specially  by  one  sane  and  wise  critic  of  life  who  was 
separated  by  the  whole  diameter  of  human  thought  from  Newman's 
political  and  ecclesiastical  views,  but  had  long  had  his  finger  upon 
the  pulse  of  England  and  was  grateful  for  every  spiritual  benefaction 
to  her  stubborn  race.  "  There  are  deaths  yet  to  come,"  wrote  the 
late  Richard  Holt  Hutton  in  the  Spectator  when  Newman  died, 
"  which  will  agitate  the  English  world  more  than  Cardinal  Newman's ; 
but  there  has  been  none,  and  will  be  none,  so  far  as  I  know,  that  will 
leave  the  world  that  really  knew  him  with  so  keen  a  sense  of  depriva 
tion,  of  a  white  star  extinguished,  of  a  sign  vanished,  of  an  age  impov 
erished,  of  a  grace  withdrawn.  To  many,  and  to  many  who  are  not 
Eoman  Catholics,  it  will  seem  the  nearest  approach  in  their  own 
experience  to  what  the  death  of  the  Apostle  John  must  have  been 
to  the  Church  of  the  Fathers,  when  the  closing  words  of  his  epistle, 
1  Little  children,  keep  yourselves  from  idols/  were  still  ringing  in 
their  ears.  .  .  .  Though  he  served  and  was  at  rest,  the  mere 
knowledge  that  he  was  living  in  the  quiet  Oratory  at  Edgbaston 
helped  men  to  realise  that  the  spiritual  world  is  even  more  real  than 
the  material  world,  and  that  in  that  lonely,  austere,  and  yet  gracious 
figure,  God  had  made  a  sign  to  Great  Britain  that  the  great  purpose 
of  life  is  a  purpose  to  which  this  life  hardly  more  than  introduces  us." 

But  it  is  best  of  all  through  his  own  words  that  we  shall  under 
stand  him.  The  remarkable  description  of  his  own  "  special  Father 
and  Patron,"  St.  Philip  Neri,  with  which  he  brings  to  a  close  his 
Lectures  upon  the  Idea  of  a  University,  is  really  a  revelation  of 
himself.  "  He  lived  " — so  the  great  words  run — "  in  an  age  as  traitor 
ous  to  the  interests  of  Catholicism  as  any  that  preceded  it,  or  can 
follow  it.  He  lived  at  a  time  when  pride  mounted  high,  and  the 
senses  held  rule;  a  time  when  kings  and  nobles  never  had  more  of 

19 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

state  and  homage,  and  never  less  of  personal  responsibility  and  peril ; 
when  mediaeval  winter  was  receding,  and  the  summer  sun  of  civilisa 
tion  was  bringing  into  leaf  and  flower  a  thousand  forms  of  luxurious 
enjoyment;  when  a  new  world  of  thought  and  beauty  had  opened 
upon  the  human  mind,  in  the  discovery  of  the  treasures  of  classic 
literature  and  art.  He  saw  the  great  and  gifted,  dazzled  by  the 
Enchantress,  and  drinking  in  the  magic  of  her  song ;  he  saw  the  high 
and  wise,  the  student  and  the  artist,  painting,  and  poetry,  and  sculp 
ture,  and  music,  and  architecture,  drawn  within  her  range,  and 
circling  round  the  abyss :  he  saw  heathen  forms  mounting  thence, 
and  forming  in  the  thick  air : — all  this  he  saw,  and  he  perceived  that 
the  mischief  was  to  be  met,  not  with  argument,  not  with  science,  not 
with  protests  and  warnings,  not  by  the  recluse  or  the  preacher,  but 
by  means  of  the  great  counter-fascination  of  purity  and  truth. 
And  so  he  contemplated  as  the  idea  of  his  mission,  not 
the  propagation  of  the  faith,  nor  the  exposition  of  doctrine,  nor  the 
catechetical  schools;  whatever  was  exact  and  systematic  pleased  him 
not;  he  put  from  him  monastic  rule  and  authoritative  speech,  as 
David  refused  the  armour  of  his  king.  No;  he  would  be  but  an 
ordinary  individual  priest  as  others:  and  his  weapons  should  be  but 
unaffected  humility  and  unpretending  love.  All  he  did  was  to  be  done 
by  the  light,  and  fervour,  and  convincing  eloquence  of  his  personal 
character  and  his  easy  conversation.  He  came  to  the  Eternal  City 
and  he  sat  himself  down  there,  and  his  home  and  his  family  gradually 
grew  up  around  him,  by  the  spontaneous  accession  of  materials  from 
without.  He  did  not  so  much  seek  his  own  as  draw  them  to  him. 
He  sat  in  his  small  room,  and  they  in  their  gay  worldly  dresses,  the 
rich  and  the  well-born,  as  well  as  the  simple  and  the  illiterate,  crowded 
into  it.  In  the  mid-heats  of  summer,  in  the  frosts  of  winter,  still 
was  he  in  that  low  and  narrow  cell  at  San  Girolamo,  reading  the 
hearts  of  those  who  came  to  him,  and  curing  their  souls'  maladies 
by  the  very  touch  of  his  hand.  It  was  a  vision  of  the  Magi  wor 
shipping  the  infant  Saviour,  so  pure  and  innocent,  so  sweet  and 
beautiful  was  he;  and  so  loyal  and  so  dear  to  the  gracious  Virgin 
Mother.  And  they  who  came  remained  gazing  and  listening,  till  at 
length,  first  one  and  then  another  threw  off  their  bravery,  and  took 

20 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

his  poor  cassock  and  girdle  instead :  or,  if  they  kept  it,  it  was  to  put 
haircloth  under  it,  or  to  take  on  them  a  rule  of  life,  while  to  the  world 
they  looked  as  before." 

Such  was  St.  Philip;  and  such,  with  a  touch  of  lofty  personal 
distinction  unknown  to  Philip,  was  Cardinal  Newman.  But  such 
character  and  such  influence  come  to  no  man  by  accident.  Newman 
in  the  Oratory  was  what  he  was,  because  of  what  his  own  inner  heart 
had  been  while  he  was  still  an  Anglican.  And  what  that  was  we 
have  earlier  words  of  his  own  to  show  us.  In  his  last  days  as  an 
Anglican,  when  the  pain  was  heavy  upon  him  of  his  approaching 
separation  from  the  friends  of  his  youth  and  from  the  Church  which 
he  loved  and  from  the  University  which  had  been  his  home,1  the 
words,  "  Man  goeth  forth  unto  his  work  and  to  his  labour  until  the 
evening,"  seem  to  have  been  often  in  his  mind.  Twice  he  preached 
from  them;  and  each  sermon  was  a  revelation  of  the  inner  and 
supreme  principle  of  his  own  life. 

" '  Blessed  are  they,' y:  — so  ran  the  conclusion  of  the  first — 
" (  Blessed  are  they  that  do  His  commandments,  that  they  may  have 
right  to  the  tree  of  life,  and  may  enter  in  through  the  gates  into  the 
city/  Blessed  will  they  be  then,  and  only  they,  who  with  the 
Apostle  have  ever  had  on  their  lips  and  in  their  hearts  the  question, 
'  Lord,  what  wilt  thou  have  me  to  do  ?'  whose  soul  '  hath  broken  out 
for  the  very  fervent  desire  that  it  hath  alway  unto  His  judgments ' ; 
who  have  '  made  haste  and  prolonged  not  the  time  to  keep  His  com 
mandments  ' ;  who  have  not  waited  to  be  hired,  nor  run  uncertainly, 
nor  beaten  the  air,  nor  taken  darkness  for  light  and  light  for  darkness, 
nor  contented  themselves  with  knowing  what  is  right,  nor  taken  com 
fort  in  feeling  what  is  good,  nor  prided  themselves  in  their  privileges, 
but  set  themselves  vigorously  to  do  God's  will. 

"  Let  us  turn  from  shadows  of  all  kinds — shadows  of  sense,  or 
shadows  of  argument  and  disputation,  or  shadows  addressed  to  our 
imagination  and  tastes.  Let  us  attempt,  through  God's  grace,  to 
advance  and  sanctify  the  inner  man.  We  cannot  be  wrong  here. 
Whatever  is  right,  whatever  is  wrong,  in  this  perplexing  world,  we 

i  "  Trinity  had  ne  ver  been  unkind  to  me.  There  used  to  be  much  snap-dragon  growing 
on  the  walls  opposite  my  freshman's  rooms  there,and  I  had  for  years  taken  it  as  the  emblem 
of  my  own  perpetual  residence  even  unto  death  in  my  University."— A pologia,  p.  237. 

•    -  21 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

must  be  right  in  '  doing  justly,  in  loving  mercy,  in  walking  humbly 
with  our  God/  in  denying  our  wills,  in  ruling  our  tongues,  in  soften 
ing  and  sweetening  our  tempers,  in  mortifying  our  lusts ;  in  learning 
patience,  meekness,  purity,  forgiveness  of  injuries  and  continuance 
in  well-doing." 

The  second  was  preached  just  after  his  resignation  of  the  living 
of  St.  Mary's.  He  himself,  and  what  life  meant  for  him — both  stand 
revealed  in  the  form  which  his  sorrow  took  as  he  uttered  what  was 
really  his  farewell  to  all  that  had  been  dear  to  him  upon  the  earth ;  to 
the  Church  of  England,  to  his  University,  to  his  friends. — "  0  mother 
of  saints !  0  school  of  the  wise !  0  nurse  of  the  heroic !  of  whom 
went  forth,  in  whom  have  dwelt,  memorable  names  of  old,  to  spread 
the  truth  abroad,  or  to  cherish  and  illustrate  it  at  home !  0  thou 
from  whom  surrounding  nations  lit  their  lamps !  0  virgin  of  Israel ! 
wherefore  dost  thou  now  sit  on  the  ground  and  keep  silence,  like  one 
of  the  foolish  women  who  were  without  oil  on  the  coming  of  the 
Bridegroom?  Where  is  now  the  ruler  in  Sion,  and  the  doctor  in  the 
temple,  and  the  ascetic  on  Carmel,  and  the  herald  in  the  wilderness, 
and  the  preacher  in  the  market-place?  ...  0  my  mother, 
whence  is  this  unto  thee,  that  thou  hast  good  things  poured  upon 
thee  and  canst  not  keep  them,  and  bearest  children,  yet  darest  not 
own  them?  Why  hast  thou  not  the  skill  to  use  their  services,  nor 
the  heart  to  rejoice  in  their  love  ?  How  is  it  that  whatever  is  generous 
in  purpose,  and  tender  or  deep  in  devotion,  thy  flower  and  thy 
promise,  falls  from  thy  bosom  and  finds  no  home  within  thine  arms? 
Who  hath  put  this  note  upon  thee  to  have  '  a  miscarrying  womb  and 
dry  breasts/  to  be  strange  unto  thine  own  flesh,  and  thine  eye  cruel 
towards  thy  little  ones  ?  Thine  own  offspring,  the  fruit  of  thy  womb, 
who  would  toil  for  thee,  thou  dost  gaze  upon  with  fear  as  though  a 
portent,  or  thou  dost  loathe  as  an  offence — at  best  thou  dost  but 
endure,  as  if  they  had  no  claim  but  on  thy  patience,  self-possession, 
and  vigilance,  to  be  rid  of  them  as  easily  as  thou  mayst.  Thou  makest 
them  (  stand  all  the  day  idle '  as  the  very  condition  of  thy  bearing 
with  them;  or  thou  biddest  them  to  be  gone  where  they  will  be  more 
welcome;  or  thou  sellest  them  for  nought  to  the  stranger  that  passes 
by.  ... 

22 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

"  And,  0  my  brethren,  0  kind  and  affectionate  hearts,  0  loving 
friends,  should  you  know  any  one  whose  lot  it  has  been,  by  writing 
or  by  word  of  mouth,  in  some  degree  to  help  you  thus  to  act;  if  he 
has  ever  told  you  what  you  knew  about  yourselves  or  what  you  did 
not  know;  has  read  to  you  your  wants  or  feelings,  and  comforted 
you  by  the  very  reading;  has  made  you  feel  that  there  was  a  higher 
life  than  this  daily  one,  and  a  brighter  world  than  that  you  see;  or 
encouraged  you,  or  sobered  you,  or  opened  a  way  to  the  inquiring, 
or  soothed  the  perplexed;  if  what  he  has  said  or  done  has  ever  made 
you  take  interest  in  him,  and  feel  well  inclined  towards  him; 
remember  such  a  one  in  time  to  come,  though  you  hear  him  not,  and 
pray  for  him,  that  in  all  things  he  may  know  God's  will,  and  at  all 
times  he  may  be  ready  to  fulfil  it." 

A  little  earlier  than  Newman — in  the  great  and  troubled  days, 
fateful  for  the  whole  of  humanity,  which  ushered  in  the  century  to 
which  Newman  belonged — there  had  stood  among  the  leaders  of 
England  another  man,  whose  life  moved  in  another  air  than 
Newman's,  but  in  that  other  air  had  followed  a  strangely  parallel 
course.  In  early  manhood  he  too  had  undergone  a  struggle  that 
shook  him  to  the  centre  of  his  being,  but  at  the  same  time  unchained 
and  aroused  the  mighty  powers  that  were  sleeping  in  him — a  struggle 
in  which  he  had  mingled  his  fate  with  causes  and  institutions 
that  go  beyond  the  individual  and  take  in  the  world.  And  when  his 
soul  had  found  its  peace,  he  too  had  taken  up  his  dwelling  apart 
from  the  noises  of  the  world ;  not,  however,  in  a  cloistral  society,  but 
in  the  company  of  still  lakes  and  whispering  woodland  and  solemn 
mountains,  above  him  the  alternate  gloom  and  glory  of  the  English 
sky  and  round  about  him  the  dalesmen's  homes  and  the  dalesmen's 
life.  He  too,  through  quiet  years,  had  held  like  Newman  high 
counsel  with  his  own  soul  and  had  lifted  up  his  heart  to  the  powers 
that  inhabit  eternity ;  nay,  in  this  he  had  gone  beyond  Newman ;  for 
he  held  counsel  with  nature  also,  and  made  his  communion  with  her 
a  means  toward — or  rather,  a  form  of — communion  with  the  eternal. 
And  he  too  had  spoken  to  the  men  of  his  generation;  had  spoken 
with  a  voice  that  in  authority,  in  loftiness,  in  austerity,  was  equal  to 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

Newman's  own,  and  far  surpassed  Newman's  in  the  catholicity  of 
elementary  and  simple  human  interest,  and  in  the  timeless  and  ageless 
power  of  beauty.  True,  if  you  had  met  him  face  to  face  he  would 
not  have  made  such  conquest  of  you  as  Newman  habitually  made 
of  all  who  met  him — unless,  indeed,  you  were  one  of  the  few  that 
without  allurement  of  external  charm  can  be  won  to  a  mighty  spirit 
by  its  own  native  greatness.  Newman's  unfailing  distinction,  his 
luminous  ease,  his  unerring  sense  of  fitness,  his  refined  and  winning 
charm,  his  personal  attractiveness,  the  splendour  of  his  gentleness 
and  the  splendour  of  his  austerity — what  trace  of  these  was  there,  or 
what  equivalent  for  them,  in  that  conversation  which  (save  with 
Coleridge  and  one  or  two  others)  was  no  medium  of  expression  either 
for  the  peace  or  for  the  passion  of  the  intense  and  brooding  soul  of 
Wordsworth  ?  And  yet  this  gaunt  and  rugged  man,  with  the  "  severe, 
worn  pressure  of  thought  about  his  temples,  a  fire  in  his  eye  (as  if 
he  sa"w  something  in  objects  more  than  the  outward  appearance),  an 
intense,  high,  narrow  forehead,  a  Eoman  nose,  cheeks  furrowed  by 
strong  purpose  and  feeling  " — this  gaunt  and  rugged  man  is  perhaps 
the  greatest  name  in  the  spiritual  history  of  the  English  race  in  the 
nineteenth  century.  He  did  that  supreme  thing  which  from  the 
beginning  of  the  world  until  now  few  men  have  done :  he  looked  upon 
i  the  world  and  upon  the  life  of  man  with  absolute  directness  and 
clearness  of  gaze.  The  abstractness  of  the  special  sciences,  the  pas 
sions  of  sectarian  theology,  the  limitations  which  the  spirit  of  the 
time  is  able  to  force  upon  men — it  was  as  if  these  things  simply  were 
not,  when  Wordsworth,  strong  in  his  solitude  at  the  heart  of  things, 
and  immovable  by  the  anger  of  his  age,  turned  his  eyes  upon  man,  and 
upon  man's  soul,  and  upon  the  facts  and  conditions  of  human  life, 
and  expressed  that  which  he  saw  in  a  poetry  which  fulfilled  his  own 
great  and  most  accurate  definition  and  was  "the  breath  and  finer 
spirit  of  all  knowledge — the  impassioned  expression  which  is  in  the 
countenance  of  all  Science." 

For  Wordsworth's  attempt  was  something  quite  other  than  to 
dream  about  nature,  and  to  weave  beautiful  fancies  around  certain 
of  its  more  winning  aspects,  and  in  those  dreams  and  fancies  to  find 
a  refuge  from  life  or  a  solace  for  life.  He  sought,  in  the  most 

24 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

genuine  sense  of  the  term,  to  know  nature;  sought  to  penetrate  to 
its  real  character  and  to  grasp  its  ultimate  meaning.  This  he  sought 
to  do  by  long  watching  and  resolute  thought;  by  sympathetic  vision; 
by  that  contemplation  which  is  a  "  revealing  agency  "  ;*  by  a  com 
munion  with  nature  which  was  like  the  friendship  of  a  human  heart 
with  a  human  heart  or  the  companionship  of  a  spirit  with  a  spirit. 
With  a  combination  of  meditation  and  perception,  unparalleled  in 
the  history  of  human  insight  save  by  Plato — meditation  resolute  to 
the  point  of  stubbornness  in  its  perseverance  and  laboriousness,  per 
ception  that  with  the  unclouded  directness  of  intuition  penetrated  to 
the  inner  nature  of  its  object — he  looked  upon  nature  and  looked 
upon  life ;  and,  looking,  saw  God  in  man,  and  saw  nature  as  the  form 
of  a  spirit  kindred  in  character  to  the  spirit  which  is  man,  and 
friendly  to  man  in  the  great  purposes  of  his  life.  And  so,  in  Words 
worth's  eyes,  man's  life,  in  its  ordinary  and  daily  course,  in  its 
elemental  duties  and  charities  and  delights,  in  its  natural  relation 
ships  and  natural  surroundings,  took  on  beauty  and  sacredness: — 
took  on  the  tenderest  beauty  and  the  deepest  sacredness  that  God 
can  give  or  the  universe  contain.  And  this  beauty  and  sacredness 
of  the  ordinary  life,  of  the  ordinary  duties  and  charities  of  life,  of 
the  ordinary  natural  surroundings  of  life,  Wordsworth  felt  not  merely 
for  himself.  He  was  able  to  make  others  feel  it.  He  had  (though 
not  continuously,  nor  without  startling  variations  in  degree)  that 
gift  which  to  such  high  and  severe  natures  is  not  always  given — the 
gift  of  artistic  beauty,  at  times  in  its  absolutely  highest  order  of 
elementary  tenderness  and  elementary  simplicity.  So  that  he  was 
able  to  cast  about  our  ordinary  life,  and  about  the  nature  which  is 
its  earthly  home,  the  supreme  consecration  of  poetic  light.  And  this 
in  a  way  peculiarly  his  own:  not  with  that  lavish  prodigality  of  the 
poetic  imagination  which  at  one  stroke  puts  the  object  that  it  beau 
tifies  out  of  touch  with  our  ordinary  thought  and  beyond  the  horizon 
of  our  daily  life ;  but  with  a  "  stern  spiritual  frugality  "2  which  at 

1  F.  W.  H.  Myers,  Wordsworth,  p.  131.    Compare  the  whole  chapter,  pp.  124-153 ;  and 
chapters  IV. -VI.  in  Mr.  Walter  Raleigh's  admirable  volume  (Wordsworth  :  London,  1903). 

2  R.  H.  Hutton,  Literary  Essays  (Macmillan,  1896),  p.  91. 

25 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

once  beautifies  and  sanctifies  its  object,  and  yet  leaves  that  object 
a  genuine  and  integral  part  of  our  human  life  upon  the  human  earth.1 

These  two  men  stand,  then,  each  in  his  own  way,  as  the  repre 
sentatives  of  one  great  principle — that  a  divine  presence  is  the  reality 
of  the  world,  and  that  the  consciousness  of  that  presence  is  the 
supreme  illumination  for  a  man's  soul. 

"Each  in  his  own  way,"  I  have  said.  And  indeed,  while  that 
truth  toward  which  they  turn  is  one,  no  two  men  upon  the  earth 
could  well  be  more  different  in  the  way  in  which  they  apprehend  it, 
or  in  the  quarters  from  which  they  turn  their  faces  toward  it.  For 
the  ways  by  which  the  soul  enters  into  union  with  greater  or  with 
ultimate  truth  are  many;  and  among  those  many  ways  are  two  which 
stand  radically  opposed.  If,  for  instance,  you  would  be  face  to  face 
with  the  heavenly  splendour  of  the  dawn,  you  may  go  out  into  the 
free  fields,  where  all  the  dewdrops  are  lustrous  for  very  purity  and 
in  the  absolute  stillness  of  early  morning  the  great  trees  stand  in 
their  solitary  and  monumental  peace  unroused  to  the  tumult  of  the 
day.  There  you  may  take  your  stand,  and  there  you  may  front  the 
heavenly  glory,  and  there,  looking  upon  it,  you  may  know  yourself 
for  a  part  of  it,  and  may  recognise  that  a  city  greater  than  Siena  is 
opening  to  you  her  heart  and  in  speech  not  alien  to  your  own  is 
declaring  to  you  once  more  your  citizenship  in  her.  That  you  may 
do.  But  you  may  do  something  very  different.  You  may  have 
come  to  distrust  yourself  utterly  and  hopelessly;  perhaps  because 
others  taught  you  that  it  is  right  to  do  so;  perhaps  because  of  long 
pain  and  long  failure.  And  hence  you  may  never  have  dared — or 
never  have  learned — to  go  about  in  the  world  with  the  open  heart  and 
the  seeing  eye  and  the  undaunted  step  of  a  son  in  his  father's  house. 
Bather  you  have  withdrawn  from  the  world  and  have  submitted 
yourself  to  an  authority  greater  than  yourself;  and  when  morning 

i  Wordsworth's  poetry  was  "not  properly  an  augury,  but  an  interpretation.  It  led 
man  up  to  the  recognition  of  his  own  greatness,  as  universalised  by  communion  with 
nature  and  intercourse  with  his  kind.  It  was  conversant,  not  with  subtleties  of  the 
imagination,  but  with  the  great,  the  obvious,  the  habitual,  with  the  common  earth,  the 
universal  sky,  the  waters  rolling  evermore,  the  abiding  social  powers  that  lift  man  out  of 
his  animal  self,  and  render  him  'magnanimous  to  correspond  with  heaven';  with  these 
restored  to  the  ancient  glory  that  belongs  to  them  in  their  intelligible  relations,  but  from 
which  the  prone  and  poring  gaze  of  a  false  philosophy  had  during  a  century  of  conceit 
been  diverted."  (T.  H.  Green,  Works,  Vol.  III.,  p.  120.) 

26 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

comes  it  is  only  through  the  gateway  or  the  deep  window  of  some 
monastic  enclosure  that  you  can  turn  your  eyes  eastward.  And  the 
unyielding  outline  of  that  cloistral  stone  it  is  that  then  determines 
and  defines  what  part  of  that  heavenly  glory,  and  how  much  of  it,  you 
shall  see. 

The  former  way  of  viewing  the  nature  which  is  in  man  and  in  the 
material  order  was  Wordsworth's.  That,  in  fact,  to  the  man  who 
looks  with  intelligent  eyes  upon  the  spiritual  history  of  mankind,  is 
what  the  name  "Wordsworth"  stands  for.  From  the  beginning 
until  now,  he  is  the  supreme  instance  of  it  among  the  races  that 
speak  English;  if  not  among  all  the  races  of  the  world.  But 
Newman's  method  was  the  other.  Himself  as  an  individual  he  had 
distrusted;  especially  had  distrusted  the  power  of  his  own  individual 
intellect  to  reach  ultimate  truth.  And  yet  there  was  in  him  an 
imperious  demand  for  the  very  truth  which  he  distrusted  his  own 
power  of  attaining,  and  for  the  guidance  which  such  truth  alone  can 
give  to  life.  From  the  beginning  it  had  been  his  prayer  and  his 
passionate  desire  that  his  soul  might  be  with  the  saints ;  not  standing 
alone  in  mere  individuality,  nor  left  to  its  own  caprices  and  mistakes, 
nor  wasted  in  some  blind  alley  of  the  world's  affairs,  nor  lost  in  some 
wandering  by-path  of  mistaken  thoughts;  but  with  the  saints — with 
the  men  by  whose  labours  the  central  path  in  the  history  of  man  has 
been  driven  through  the  midst  of  the  years.  And  slowly  there  had 
dawned  upon  him  that  mighty  vision  which  to  such  a  man  has  the 
power  of  absolute  compulsion.  An  institution  august  with  solem 
nities  of  ancient  prayer,  august  with  a  thousand  sanctities  and  a 
thousand  heroic  memories,  august  with  mighty  names  innumerable 
and  mighty  deeds,  the  home  of  saints  and  the  guardian  of  belief, 
drew  him  to  herself  and  subdued  to  herself  all  his  heart  and  made 
him  in  humility  and  obedience  her  son.  To  her,  with  a  sense  of 
gladness  and  of  rest,  he  gave  himself  and  gave  the  keeping  of  his 
life.  And  so  he  found  rest;  and  having  found  rest  was  able  to  do, 
more  positively  and  constructively  than  before,  the  work  which  it  lay 
in  him  to  do  for  the  men  of  his  day. 

But  the  price  was  a  dear  one ;  and  it  was  paid  still  more  by  those 
who  sat  at  his  feet  than  by  himself.  For  in  precisely  that  side  of 

27 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

his  work  which  most  deeply  concerned  the  men  of  England,  his  true 
strength  was  veiled.  The  things  that  he  himself  had  learned  so 
thoroughly,  and  that  all  men  need  to  learn — things  universal,  essen 
tial,  elemental,  catholic — he  preferred  to  base  upon  the  authority  of  an 
earthly  dogma  and  an  earthly  institution ;  and  to  mingle  with  them,  in 
obedience  to  that  same  authority,  things  not  universal,  not  essential, 
not  elemental,  and  therefore  not  catholic.  So  that  those  who  hear 
him  have  always  to  separate  that  in  his  words  which  belongs  to  essen 
tial  eternity  from  that  which  belongs  to  the  party  interest  of  a  magnifi 
cent  but  sectarian  priesthood. 

And  to  this  so  radical  difference  between  the  two  men  in  their 
method  of  apprehending  truth,  there  corresponded  a  difference  in 
their  manner  of  expressing  it.  Wordsworth,  having  "  seen  into 
the  life  of  things  "  by  that  sort  of  companionship  with  them  which 
passes  over  into  a  comprehension  of  their  inner  and  ultimate  reality, 
was,  in  his  expression  of  what  he  had  thus  seen,  a  poet.  And  that 
in  the  true  and  most  strict  sense  of  the  word.  He  was  not  a  man 
who  wrought  out  a  system  of  philosophy  or  of  theology,  and  then 
gave  to  it  an  alien  garb  of  more  or  less  successful  rhythmic  utterance. 
He  was  not  even  a  man  who  lived — to  use  Mr.  Stopford  Brooke's 
fine  metaphor1 — in  that  "  mingled  region  "  of  poetry  where  "  its 
waves  and  currents  near  the  coast  receive  the  deep  streams  of  religious 
and  philosophic  thought."  His  voyage  and  his  home  were  upon  its 
"  central  and  lonely  deep,"  where  poetry  is  poetry  and  nothing  else. 
Hence  when  Wordsworth  is  here  spoken  of  as  among  the  greatest 
of  the  spiritual  leaders  of  the  English  race,  the  Wordsworth  that  is 
meant  is  Wordsworth  the  poet.  He  was  a  captain  of  the  spirit,  was 
among  the  greatest  of  all  captains  of  the  spirit,  because  he  exercised, 
and  in  exercising,  supremely  a  certain  supreme  function — the  function 
of  the  sacred  poet.  But  Newman,  meeting  God  in  the  inner  heart, 
was  as  characteristically  and  as  inevitably  a  prophet,  in  the  strictest 
sense  of  that  great  word.  To  impress — I  had  almost  said,  to  force — 
his  consciousness  of  a  divine  presence  and  a  divine  commandment 
upon  the  men  of  his  generation,  making  no  slightest  particle  of  con 
cession  either  to  their  practical  or  to  their  theoretical  materialism, 

i  Hibbert  Journal,  No.  1  (October,  1902),  p.  62. 
28 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

was  the  supreme  business  of  his  life.  Kesolutely  he  set  the  whole 
of  life  in  the  light  of  ultimate  eternity.  Unflinchingly  he  insisted 
that  every  interest,  every  ambition,  every  affection,  every  dominant 
fashion  and  accepted  tendency,  should  answer  at  that  bar  for  its  life. 
Authoritatively,  uncompromisingly,  in  season  and  out  of  season,  that 
voice  and  that  pen,  and,  above  all,  that  solitary  and  devoted  life, 
declared  that  we  men  are  living  our  lives  in  a  divine  presence;  and 
that  that  divine  presence  is  the  one  essential  reality  with  which  in  our 
lives  we  have  to  do,  and  obedience  to  its  purpose  and  commandment 
the  one  business  of  life  which  can  claim  in  any  sense  to  be  of 
importance. 

Different  enough,  then,  the  two  men  were: — different  in  individual 
habit  and  personal  presence;  different  in  the  region  and  climate  of 
their  minds ;  different  in  their  ways,  as  of  approaching  and  appre 
hending,  so  also  of  expressing,  truth.  But  here  our  main  concern 
is  not  with  these  differences  but  with  that  in  which  they  agreed; 
with  their  consciousness  of  a  divine  presence  and  of  that  presence 
as  the  ultimate  reality  of  the  world  and  of  our  life. 

II. 

Once,  among  the  men  from  whom  we  moderns  draw  our  blood  and 
our  speech,  and  in  whose  places  we  now  stand,  such  a  consciousness, 
under  the  more  limited  of  the  two  forms  just  described,  dominated  life. 
A  "consciousness  of  a  divine  presence  and  of  that  presence  as  the 
ultimate  reality  of  the  world  and  of  our  life,"  and  a  consequent  con 
sciousness  of  the  supremacy  of  spiritual  interests,  were  central  and 
determinative  among  the  forces  that  made  the  mediasval  world  what 
it  was.  So  far  as  the  religious  spirit  of  their  time  lived  in  them, 
mediaeval  men  habitually  looked  upon  themselves  as  members  of  an 
eternal  order  and  citizens  of  an  eternal  kingdom.  They  worked  "  as 
seeing  One  who  is  invisible,"  and  as  "not  being  disobedient  to  a 
heavenly  vision."  They  remembered  that  in  order  to  live  we  must 
die,  and  that  in  every  department  of  life  the  divine  ordinance  is  the 
cross  with  its  principle  of  self-renunciation  and  of  living  "  not  to  be 

29 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

ministered  unto,  but  to  minister."  They  lived  "  under  the  power  of 
the  world  to  come;"  and  if  this  present  world  showed  itself  to  their 
understanding  as  the  foe  of  that  world,  they  did  not  shrink  from  the 
separation,  but  made  strong  their  souls,  and  denied  the  present  world 
and  all  its  love,  and  walked  in  it  as  strangers  and  pilgrims.  This 
was  in  their  hearts ;  and  in  the  great  confession  of  their  day,  the  book 
De  Imitatione  Christi,  it  spoke  itself  into  words  for  ever;  but  it 
was  no  mere  maxim  for  meditation  and  confession — it  was  a  genuine 
principle  of  unity  of  life.  For  that  generation  as  truly  as  any  other 
"  went  forth  unto  its  work  and  to  its  labour  until  the  evening  " : — 
nay,  more  truly,  for  the  middle  age  stands  as  in  all  the  history  of  the 
world  pre-eminently  the  age  of  great  workmen ;  not  of  great  machines, 
nor  of  great  financial  combinations  standing  over  against  sullen  and 
reluctant  labourers,  but  of  great  workmen  and  of  the  delight  in 
craftsmanship  which  great  workmen  can  feel.  And  that  which  was 
in  their  hearts  and  in  their  confession — that  habitual  remembrance 
of  God  and  craving  to  be  at  one  with  Him,  that  incessant  and 
insistent  vision  of  a  world  to  come  and  of  a  divine  order  which 
earthly  eyes  cannot  apprehend  but  which  is  manifest  in  the  cross — 
was  also  in  their  action  and  achievement.  They  worked  greatly  in 
the  field  of  the  intellect;  and  the  effort  was  to  gather  all  science 
into  one  thoroughly-articulated  knowledge  of  God,  which  in  part 
should  illuminate,  but  still  more  should  rebuke,  the  ways  of  this 
present  world.  They  worked  with  equal  greatness  in  the  field  of  art; 
and  there  too — though  it  is  specially  in  art  that  the  human  soul 
rejoices  in  its  own  powers  and  in  the  exercise  of  them  for  their  own 
sake — they  were  under  the  banner  of  the  world  to  come.  For  when 
they  painted,  it  was  the  judgment,  the  heaven,  the  hell,  which  give  to 
this  life  its  awful  significance;  or  it  was  the  saints  in  their  conflict 
with  the  world;  or  our 'Lord  submitting  Himself  to  the  helplessness 
of  infancy,  or  undergoing  the  death  of  the  cross,  or  rising  in  that 
resurrection  which  showed  another  world  triumphant  over  the  ways 
of  this.  Or  when  they  built — and-  they  were  for  the  sustained 
spiritual  passion  that  animated  their  work  the  greatest  builders  in 
the  history  of  the  world — their  building  culminated  in  houses 
of  prayer  which  lift  themselves  almost  out  of  connexion  with  the 

30 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

earth  and  express  in  the  most  stately  of  all  man's  languages  the 
majesty  of  heavenly  things  and  the  upward  movement  of  the  soul 
in  prayer  toward  that  majesty.  Even  when  they  sang,  romance  and 
folk-song — the  delight  of  the  young  in  earthly  love,  and  the  illumina 
tion  of  this  present  life  by  the  na'ive  imagination — were  felt  to  stand 
half-unconsecrated  without  the  gate,  while  within  the  singing  was 
that  of  men  whose  vigil  was  for  another  country  and  whose  love  was 
set  upon  a  farther  shore.  And  as  were  the  works  so  were  the  men. 
If  a  man  arose,  at  once  to  embody  the  ideals  of  the  age  and  to  dom 
inate  its  higher  imagination,  it  was  Bernard  controlling  Europe  from 
that  lowly  cell  where  as  the  proper  business  of  his  life  he  sought  the 
mystic  vision  of  God;  or  it  was  Francis,  with  his  humility,  his  self- 
denial,  his  pity  and  tenderness  and  loving  ministration  to  the  poor, 
his  canticle  of  praise  to  our  Lord  for  "  our  sister,  the  death  of  the 
body "  and  for  "  all  those  who  forgive  one  another  for  His  love's 
sake."  Pilgrims  of  eternity,  encamped  for  one  troubled  night  upon 
this  shore — such  the  men  over  whom  the  spirit  of  that  age  had  power 
felt  themselves  to  be.  The  "  lyrical  cry  "  of  their  life  was  that  of 
Israel ;  but  the  cry  wrung  from  solitary  hearts  in  Israel  by  the  afflic 
tions  of  the  righteous  and  the  measureless  prosperity  of  the  wicked 
and  the  desperation  and  disaster  of  Israel's  struggle  for  racial  exist 
ence,  had  become  in  them  a  settled  conviction  and  an  habitual  temper : 

Thou  shalt  guide  me  with  thy  counsel, 

And  afterward  receive  me  to  glory. 

Whom  have  I  in  heaven  but  thee  ? 

And  there  is  none  upon  earth  that  I  desire  beside  thee. 

My  flesh  and  my  heart  faileth  : 

But  God  is  the  strength  of  my  heart,  and  my  portion  for  ever. 

God  was  the  strength  of  their  heart;  God  and  the  world  to  come 
were  the  realities  that  filled  their  thought.  And  precisely  from  this 
arose  what  we  have  just  had  to  see :  though  the  world  was  not  their 
home,  yet,  so  far  as  they  looked  upon  it  at  all,  they  were  worthy 
workmen  in  its  affairs.  The  fact  that  they  viewed  the  world  from  a 
point  high  above  it,  gave  them  alike  in  thought  and  in  action  a 
double  strength:  gave  them,  first,  the  loftiness  of  mind  which  arises 
out  of  a  great  devotion — and  the  devotion  of  the  unworldly  to  their 

31 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

causes  is,  as  the  inner  soul  of  action,  a  power  unspeakably  greater 
than  ambition;  gave  them,  secondly,  the  spirit  of  comprehensive 
unity.  Not  only  did  they  seek  the  unity,  under  a  divine  idea,  of  the 
intellectual  outlook  upon  life;  they  sought  a  still  greater  goal — the 
unity,  in  a  divine  order,  of  the  social  organisation  of  life.  The  con 
scious  or  unconscious  aspiration  after  that  twofold  unity  was,  to  their 
mind  its  inner  power,  to  their  society  the  highest  of  its  organising 
principles. 

In  this  way — a  way  narrow  but  profound  and  masterful — a  con 
sciousness  of  the  supremacy  of  the  spirit  and  of  spiritual  interests 
once  dominated  life.  And  of  the  men  who  bore  that  consciousness 
we  are  the  children;  we  stand  in  the  succession  of  their  blood  and  of 
their  labour.  But  we  view  the  world  and  live  our  life  in  a  temper 
radically  different  from  theirs.  The  men  amongst  us  who  view  life 
in  a  way  similar  to  theirs,  or  in  a  way  kindred  to  theirs  but  broader, 
are  not  the  representative  men,  the  men  whose  spirit  is  an  expression 
and  epitome  of  a  temper  which  clearly  or  unclearly  is  common  to  us 
all — the  men  who  are  to  our  day  what  Bernard  or  Francis  was  to 
his.  It  is  true  (now  that  the  immediate  personal  conflicts  are  over) 
that  we  are  very  willing  to  listen  to  such  men  as  Newman ;  still  more 
willing  to  listen  to  such  men  as  Wordsworth.  Indeed  we  listen  to 
them  with  an  urbanity,  a  completeness  of  intellectual  toleration,  which 
in  mediaeval  days  one  at  least  of  them  would  have  looked  for  in  vain. 
We  give  them,  in  fact,  everything  they  ask — except  the  one  supreme 
thing  which  they  demand  most  of  all.  We  appreciate  the  excellence 
of  their  literary  workmanship.  We  do  justice  to  the  height  of  their 
characters.  We  are  grateful  to  them  for  the  grace  and  the  dignity 
which  they  have  added  to  our  life,  and  for  the  honour  accruing  from 
their  work  to  the  English  tongue.  We  listen  gladly  to  the  one  as  the 
bearer  of  a  poetic  vision.  We  hearken  respectfully  to  the  other  as  the 
prophet  of  what,  with  the  forbearing  courtesy  of  well-bred  men  but 
with  hearts  untouched,  we  call  mystic  piety.  Only  let  us  view  them 
as  a  specially  noble  sort  of  dreamers,  weaving  around  the  hard  core 
of  the  actual  reality  of  things  a  garment  of  fancy  and  high  emotion 
which  adorns  and  dignifies  its  surface  but  can  make  no  claim  to 

32 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

express  its  true  nature: — then  they  are  quite  intelligible  to  us; 
indeed,  with  our  sense  of  the  bareness  and  hardness  of  our  life,  not 
only  intelligible  but  very  estimable.  But  as  soon  as  we  are  told  that 
their  words  are  the  plain  and  simple  truth  about  our  world,  and  about 
the  meaning  of  our  life  in  it,  and  about  our  actual  everyday  affairs; 
as  soon  as  we  are  told  that  their  valuation  of  the  things  we  modern 
men  are  all  striving  for  is  the  true  valuation: — at  that  instant  we 
feel  a  great  gulf  fixed  between  us  and  them;  a  gulf  so  deep  as  to 
preclude  either  mutual  understanding  or  mutual  sympathy  or  a  com 
mon  aim  in  life. 

So  radical  is  the  difference  in  temper  between  us  and  the  mediaeval 
men  whose  children  we  are.  But  a  glance  at  the  history  which  lies 
between  us  and  them  will  show  that  the  change  was  inevitable.  For 
in  their  position  there  lay  a  double  difficulty.  They  forgot  certain 
great  works  of  God  which  cannot  be  forgotten  without  shattering 
soon  or  late  the  man  or  the  age  or  the  institution  that  forgets  them. 
First,  they  forgot  the  natural  world.  With  all  their  understanding 
of  the  supremacy  of  the  spirit  and  of  spiritual  interests,  they  did  not 
understand  that  nature  also  teaches  that  supremacy,  and  is  herself, 
to  those  who  know  her  as  she  is,  and  are  able  to  use  her  wisely,  a 
means  toward  it.  And  because  their  position  thus  did  injustice  to 
nature  and  the  natural  order,  the  time  came  when  the  man  of  science, 
the  poet,  and  the  ordinary  man,  had,  each  in  his  own  way,  to  rebel 
against  it.  Secondly,  save  to  rebuke  it,  they  almost  forgot  the  natural 
soul  of  man.  But  that  soul  contains  powers  which  soon  or  late  must 
come  to  their  right:  powers  of  affection  and  of  passion;  artistic 
powers  and  powers  of  the  systematic  intellect;  and  that  power  of 
initiative  which  makes  man,  like  the  God  from  whom  he  comes,  in 
his  own  order  a  creator  and  founder.  To  a  few  of  these  capacities 
of  the  natural  soul,  the  mediseval  system,  it  is  true,  gave  magnificent 
scope — specially  in  the  art  of  building;  but  most  of  them  it  scorned 
or  repressed;  and,  by  its  tendency  to  change  faith  from  an  energy 
of  the  divinely  illuminated  individual  soul  into  a  systematic  creed 
laid  down  by  an  authoritative  institution,  it  sinned  so  deeply  against 
human  nature  as  to  drive  men  at  last  into  the  modern  position  that 
the  only  illumination  worth  having  is  that  of  a  free  man,  that  even 

4  33 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

a  heavenly  vision  is  not  to  be  received  unless  it  come  as  to  a  free 
spirit. 

So  that  the  man  who  studies  history,  however  much  he  love  that 
age  of  great  workmen  and  of  great  workmanship  and  of  great  souls 
whose  citizenship  was  in  heaven,  has  to  insist  that  the  age  could  not 
continue.  And,  at  first  sight,  the  student  of  history  seems  able  to 
go  still  farther ;  seems  able  to  point  out  the  way  in  which  the  advance 
should  have  been  made.  It  should  have  been  by  growth,  not  by  rebel 
lion  and  revolution.  The  principle  should  not  have  been  thrown  away 
because  it  had  been  practised  too  narrowly.  With  the  great  achieve 
ment  of  mediaeval  men  a  complete  break  should  not  have  been  made. 
Their  light  should  not  have  been  treated  as  though  it  were  merely  and 
simply  darkness;  rather  it  should  have  been  retained  in  its  integrity 
but  freed  from  its  limitations.  Men  should  live  still  as  citizens  of 
the  world  to  come,  but  recognising  that  of  the  world  to  come  the 
present  world  is  an  organic  part.  The  divine  idea  should  still  be 
seen  as  the  one  important  reality  in  human  life;  but  it  should  be 
remembered  that  the  stage  in  the  realisation  of  that  idea  at  which  we 
men  can  directly  and  sincerely  labour,  is  the  one  found  in  the  causes 
and  activities  which  make  up  the  life  of  a  normal  man  in  this  present 
world — the  life  of  the  good  neighbour,  good  citizen,  good  churchman. 
Or,  to  put  all  this  in  one  word,  the  true  way  of  advance  from  the 
mediaeval  position  was  to  pass  from  the  type  of  insight  and  of 
spiritual  consciousness  represented  in  modern  form  by  Newman  to 
that  represented  by  Wordsworth. 

But  whatever  the  reason  be,  the  history  of  the  universe — so  far, 
at  any  rate,  as  the  history  of  man  on  this  earth  is  a  part  of  it  and 
an  index  to  its  nature — does  not  go  on  by  any  such  direct  and  easy 
method.  The  God  from  whom  we  come  shows  Himself  in  His  work 
a  Lord  of  Hosts.  He  develops  the  powers  of  His  creatures  and  the 
life  of  His  universe  by  calling  forth  the  mighty  opposites  that  He  has 
implanted  in  the  natures  of  things,  so  that  each  develops  its  truth 
and  its  power  against  the  other,  until  at  last  the  very  stress  and  pain 
of  the  conflict  lead  men  to  that  still  wider  truth  in  which  justice  is 
done  to  the  incomplete  truth  which  each  side  had  and  was  developing. 
Fortunately  or  unfortunately,  it  is  as  true  in  the  kingdom  of  the 

34 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

spirit  as  it  is  in  the  physical  order  that  plain  daylight  is  a  thing 
most  complex.  All  the  great  kinds  of  light  (if  one  may  so  speak) 
have  to  be  discovered  and  set  in  their  places,  by  hard  labour — some 
times  by  hard  fighting  and  many  wounds  and  wanderings — before 
that  day  can  come  in  which  all  the  types  of  light  will  blend  in  the 
illumination  which  alone  in  the  full  sense  of  the  word  can  be  called 
truth. 

And  so  it  was  that  the  spiritual  splendour  which  in  the  mediaeval 
dawn  of  our  history  gleamed  through  cloud  and  storm  and  over  the 
brute  earth,  was  not,  in  the  direct  fashion  mentioned  an  instant  ago, 
to  deepen  into  a  more  inclusive  day.  Age  after  age  was  to  come,  each 
in  its  own  way  a  very  antithesis  to  the  mediaeval.  First  came  the 
Renaissance.  Men  flung  themselves  with  absolute  delight  upon  the 
resources  of  this  present  life,  and  for  the  first  time  after  many  cen 
turies  lived  as  masters  and  lords  of  this  present  world.  New  worlds 
they  discovered  in  themselves;  new  worlds  across  the  sea;  and  in  the 
products  of  ancient  culture,  the  most  alluring  of  all  their  new  worlds. 
They  loved  the  world,  and  the  sorrow  in  their  words  was  because 
upon  all  the  objects  of  their  delight  they  found  it  written  that  the 
world  and  the  fashion  of  it  pass  away.  Augustine's  mourning 
was  that  he  had  lived  in  the  things  of  the  world  so  long  and  had 
found  God  so  late :  "  I  have  loved  Thee  late,  Thou  Beauty  so  old 
and  so  new;  I  have  loved  Thee  late!"  But  the  deep  undernote  of 
lament  in  the  greater  Renaissance  writings  was  because  the  glorious 
children  of  the  earth,  in  the  midst  of  their  life  found  themselves  to 
be  in  death.  And  yet  their  love  of  the  world  was  no  ignoble  passion ; 
their  delight  in  the  things  of  the  world  had  in  it  such  a  magnificence 
of  mind  that  it  was  a  religion  rather  than  a  slavery;  and  to-day,  it 
is  the  better  men  and  not  the  worse  who  in  hidden  places  of  their 
souls  have  still  the  banner  of  the  Renaissance  flying.  But  already, 
unknown  to  the  men  of  the  Renaissance,  profounder  and  more  terrific 
forces  than  their  view  of  life  comprehended,  were  "  toiling  in  the 
gloom,"  and  soon  throughout  Europe,  first  in  religion  and  then  in 
political  affairs,  the  trumpets  were  calling  to  war.  In  the  end  that 
war  exhausted  or  destroyed  nearly  all  that  was  noble  in  the  forces 
which  had  given  rise  to  it,  and  left  for  the  close  of  the  seventeenth 

35 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

century  and  the  earlier  part  of  the  eighteenth,  a  world  degraded  and 
desolate,  a  world  that  slowly  regained  the  solid  comforts  of  life,  and 
acquired  a  certain  hard  and  polished  culture,  but  in  which,  probably 
to  a  greater  extent  than  in  any  other  Western  century  since  Eome  fell, 
the  visible  and  established  elements  of  society,  churches  and  theo 
logians,  rulers  and  ruled,  forgot  God.  And  then  came  our  own  day. 
It  dawned  at  Paris;  dawned  in  blood,  and  with  mighty  passions- 
passions  social  and  political  and  one  might  almost  say  religious, 
which  spread  their  energy  throughout  the  world;  but  it  proved  in 
the  end,  and  not  unnaturally,  to  be  the  day  of  the  scientific  intellect. 
That  intellect  had  long  been  held  in  check:  alike  in  the  age  of 
passionate  devotion  to  the  humanities,  and  in  the  age  of  war,  and 
in  the  hard  age  that  had  no  place  either  for  the  enthusiasms  of  the 
pure  intellect  or  for  the  devotion  of  the  mind  to  nature.  But  now 
at  last  it  came  to  its  own;  or  rather,  as  is  usual  in  such  cases,  to 
more  than  its  own.  Without  the  lofty  Renaissance  passion,  without 
the  special  Renaissance  delight  in  life,  free  also  from  much  of  the 
eighteenth-century  hardness  of  spirit,  it  set  itself  to  master  the  world. 
As  an  investigating  intellect,  it  made  itself  at  home  with  the  facts 
and  laws  of  nature ;  as  a  contriving  intelligence,  it  reduced  the  powers 
of  nature  to  practical  uses — bringing  in  at  last  the  day  of  which  Bacon 
prophesied  with  such  large  magnificence  of  speech,  but  which  prob 
ably  he  would  view  with  a  certain  lordly  contempt,  if,  with  Eliza 
bethan  memories,  he  were  suddenly  to  come  to  life  in  it. 

Such  an  intervening  history  places  more  than  the  mere  lapse  of 
time  between  us  and  the  mediaeval  men  who  won  from  chaos,  and 
established  with  settled  forms  and  laws,  that  living  and  thinking 
which  it  is  now  our  business  to  carry  on.  When  we  compare  our 
mind,  and  the  world  of  our  life,  with  their  world  and  their  mind, 
we  may  sum  up  the  loss  and  gain  in  two  broad  statements.  First, 
while  both  in  spirit  and  in  skill  of  hand  we  are  poorer  workmen  than 
the  mediaeval  men  were,  yet  we  have  a  mastery  of  this  present  world 
which  they  had  not.  We  have  explored,  as  they  could  not,  the  possi 
bilities  of  the  present  life,  and  have  entered,  both  intellectually  and 
practically,  into  possession  of  the  two  great  kingdoms  which  it  con 
tains — on  the  one  side,  the  kingdom  of  nature  with  its  powers;  on 

36 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

the  other,  the  kingdom  of  humane  culture  and  of  the  higher  passions 
and  affections.  Other  men  might  use  the  materials  which  the  world 
affords  in  building  great  houses  of  prayer  to  testify  of  another  world 
and  by  their  very  majesty  to  shame  into  nothingness  the  vanities  of 
this;  we  have  found  that  those  materials  can  be  used  in  erecting  and 
adorning  mansions  for  the  present  habitation  of  our  own  souls.  And, 
having  such  houses  for  our  souls,  we  cannot  regard  ourselves,  while 
upon  the  earth,  as  strangers  and  sojourners.  Eather  we  feel  ourselves 
to  be  citizens  of  no  mean  city;  a  city  which  we  have  placed  on  sure 
foundations  by  taking  as  the  servants  of  our  life  the  powers  of  nature, 
and  as  the  tutors  of  our  minds  the  laws  of  nature. 

But  secondly,  in  this  very  conquest  of  the  world  we  have  to  a 
great  extent  become  lost  in  the  world.  We  have  made  the  earth  our 
own ;  but  have  become  too  much  confined  to  it.  It  goes,  indeed,  with 
out  saying,  that  the  latter  does  not  follow  logically  from  the  former. 
For  the  discovery  of  the  greatness  of  the  present  life  is  absolutely 
no  reason  for  ceasing  to  live  the  great  present  life  under  the  power  of 
some  still  greater  life  to  come.  The  connexion,  as  already  has  been 
indicated,  is  one  not  of  logic  in  the  narrower  sense,  but  of  that  greater 
logic  which  is  history.  The  Eenaissance  revolt  contributed  to  it  in 
one  way;  the  Thirty  Years'  War  in  another;  the  eighteenth  century 
in  still  another.  And  we  ourselves  managed  badly;  we  flung  our 
selves  so  eagerly  into  the  new  fields  and  the  new  life  that  our  hands 
became  subdued  to  what  they  were  working  in.  But  here  it  is  with 
the  fact,  rather  than  with  the  fault,  that  we  are  concerned.  And 
the  fact  may  be  considered  as  moving  in  two  spheres,  a  narrower  and 
a  wider. 

(«) 

The  narrower  sphere  is  that  of  thought.  Here  the  new  situation 
consists  in  a  changed  view  of  the  field  of  knowledge.  The  things 
that  we  regard  as  certain — the  things  that  are  the  objects  of  reliable 
and  indisputable  insight — are  things  strictly  of  this  world.  We  have 
the  knowledge  of  nature;  that  is  assured  and  established  science. 
Some  of  us  feel  that  this  assured  science  permits  something  farther; 
something  which,  if  any  one  so  chooses,  may  be  called  a  knowledge 

37 


THE    STUDY    OF    JSTATUKE 

of  God,  but  would  more  properly  be  called  a  faith  or  a  hope.  Others 
of  us  believe  that  our  science  of  nature  does  not  permit  such  farther 
"knowledge"  or  "faith."  But  what  we  all  seem  agreed  upon  is 
that  the  two  are  essentially  different  things ;  the  knowledge  of  nature 
;,  and  the  knowledge  of  God  cannot  be  regarded  as  essentially  akin,  as 
two  stages  in  one  growing  insight,  or  as  two  levels  in  one  and  the 
same  structure. 

In  this  shattering  of  the  former  unity  of  science,  and  this  limita 
tion  of  knowledge  in  the  strict  sense  of  the  term  to  one  of  the  frag 
ments,  the  leading  influence  has  been  the  modern  study  of  nature. 
But  we  must  notice  with  special  care  how  the  exertion  of  such  an 
influence  has  been  rendered  possible.  It  has  been  made  possible, 
not  from  one  side  but  from  two :  from  the  side  of  the  men  of  natural 
science  themselves;  and  from  the  side  of  the  theological  leaders  of 
the  church. 

First,  from  the  side  of  the  men  of  science.  The  movement  of 
thought  by  which  many  of  these  passed  from  their  knowledge  of 
nature  to  a  materialistic  or  agnostic  view  of  the  world  has  already 
been  described.1  It  is  sufficient  here  to  indicate  the  result.  This 
was  the  placing  before  modern  men  of  a  teaching  about  life  and  the 
world,  which  was  not  new,  indeed,  but  which  now  took  on  a  new  power. 
For  it  was  inculcated  now  by  men  deservedly  of  great  influence ;  men 
of  wide  knowledge,  of  disciplined  mind,  of  undoubted  honesty,  the 
leaders  in  the  most  striking  and  most  evidently  successful  of  the 
intellectual  labours  of  modern  times.  Moreover  the  movement  of 
thought  by  which  it  was  now  reached  (though  really  involving  a 
great  oversight)  was  so  direct  that  the  resultant  view  seemed  to  be 
based  immediately  upon  established  and  indisputable  science.  That 
the  physical  process  is  continuous  and  its  sum  of  energy  constant; 
that  it  must  lead  our  planet  soon  or  late  to  a  dead  eternity  in  which 
self-conscious  life  can  have  no  footing: — these  (so  that  resultant 
view  may  be  stated)  are  the  things  that  are  beyond  doubt,  and  upon 
them  anything  which  is  to  be  a  sober  and  reliable  wisdom  for  the 
conduct  of  life  must  base  itself.  Hence  it  is  no  longer  open  to  us 
to  regard  ourselves  as  other  than  beings  of  the  present  world;  nor 

1  Supra,  pp.  4,  5. 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

to  regard  as  other  than  visionary  any  view  which  makes  "  the  great 
purpose  of  life  "  to  be  "  a  purpose  to  which  this  life  hardly  more  than 
introduces  us."  If  you  would  know  the  true  character  and  meaning 
and  destiny  of  human  life,  there  is  but  one  way  to  gain  the  knowledge : 
you  must  consider  the  total  system  of  which  that  life  is  a  part;  that 
is  to  say,  you  must  consider  the  system  of  natural  facts,  out  of  which 
it  arises  and  in  which  it  is  lived.  If  you  ask :  But  was  it  not  those 
very  facts  that  Wordsworth  considered?  the  answer  comes  in  very 
direct  words :  "His  views  were  a  poet's  fancies ;  fancies  clad  in 
beauty,  but  none  the  less  fancies.  And  the  dreams  of  a  poet,  or  the 
visions  of  hearts  that  cling  to  life  and  to  love,  cannot  take  precedence 
of  established  and  disinterested  knowledge.  Such  knowledge  it  is 
that  we  have  in  the  sciences  of  nature,  and  it  affords  no  ground  for 
visions  and  hopes  that  go  beyond  this  present  life.  Modern  science, 
in  one  word,  has  shattered  old  religion." 

But  as  was  indicated  above,  the  fact  that  the  modern  scientific  *' 
movement  has  contributed  to  the  materialisation  of  thought  and  of 
life  has  been^made  possible,  not  only  from  the  side  of  the  men  of 
science,  but  also  from  the  side  of  the  theological  leaders  of  the  church. 
And  the  latter  is  the  greater  and  the  sadder  story.  Theology,  upon 
the  older  conception  of  it,  included  all  knowledge.  It  meant  the 
whole  of  science  brought  to  the  unity  of  a  supreme  and  ultimate 
principle;  brought  to  unity  in  and  as  a  knowledge  of  God.  Hence 
the  theologians  were  bound  by  their  own  conception  of  their  task 
to  be  catholic-minded,  to  be  hospitable  to  all  the  orders  of  science. 
The  notion  of  theology  as  a  single  special  science  standing  among 
the  other  special  sciences,  and  at  war  with  some  of  them,  was  a 
notion  which — if  they  could  have  formed  it — they  would  have  rejected 
as  monstrous.  On  the  contrary,  it  was  only  by  taking  all  the  sciences 
as  their  "  parish,"  and  considering  each  as  part  of  the  knowledge  of 
God,  that  they  could  fulfil  their  function.  Hence — inevitable  as  was 
their  failure  to  complete  their  science — they  were  qualified  by  the  very 
nature  of  their  attempt  to  perform  one  great  service  for  humanity. 
If  there  came  an  intellectual  movement — whether  the  recovery  of 
Aristotelian  treatises  or  the  founding  of  new  sciences — bringing  with 
it  a  body  of  knowledge  new  but  convincing  to  tfye  age,  they,  as  theo- 

39 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

logians,  were  the  men  at  once  obliged  and  qualified  to  receive  it,  to 
interpret  it,  and  to  set  it  in  its  place  in  the  one  knowledge  of  God. 

It  was  precisely  such  a  work  of  interpretation  that  the  modern 
world  needed  from  its  theologians.  There  had  come  a  great,  a  trium 
phantly  successful,  scientific  movement,  giving  us  a  better  acquaint 
ance  than  ever  before  with  that  work  of  God  which  is  the  natural 
world.  The  duty  of  theology  was  to  receive  with  catholicity  of  mind 
that  new  body  of  science,  to  penetrate  to  its  real  significance,  and  so 
to  give  it  its  place  in  the  one  body  of  man's  knowledge  of  God.  To 
have  received  in  that  way  the  sciences  of  nature,  to  have  viewed  sub 
specie  aeternitatis  their  work,  and  so  to  have  given  to  them  their 
"  divine  interpretation  " — this,  and  this  alone,  would  have  given  us 
what  we  needed.  For  what  we  needed  was  not  polemic,  but  a  point 
of  view  from  which  we  could  look  upon  both  sides  of  the  conflict,  and 
see  into  the  ultimate  harmony  in  one  rational  world  of  the  great 
truths  which  seemed  to  have  come  from  radically  different  worlds  and 
to  be  in  death-struggle  with  each  other. 

That  we  needed;  and  that  the  theology  of  Albert  or  of  Thomas, 
recognising  its  high  prerogative  of  being  the  guide  of  the  human  race 
in  those  spiritual  crises  which  the  revolutions  of  time  bring  forth, 
would  have  striven  with  all  its  might  to  give.  But  the  greater  prin 
ciples  and  greater  procedures  of  those  masters  had  long  ceased  to 
obtain;  their  conception  of  theology,  with  its  demand  for  a  compre 
hensive  view  of  the  world  and  consequently  for  a  catholic  attitude 
toward  all  sciences  that  deal  with  the  world,  had  long  been  forgotten ; 
or  if  remembered,  was  remembered  with  grave  dislike.  "  Systematic 
theology/'  as  it  was  when  the  minds  were  being  formed  of  those  who 
are  now  doing  the  world's  work,  would  have  been  remarkable  to  St. 
Thomas  chiefly  for  its  limitations,  for  its  absent  problems  and  absent 
provinces;  he  would  have  shuddered  alike  ^  at  the  narrowness  of  its 
scope  and  at  its  dread  of  the  greater  enginery  of  the  intellect.  It  is 
impossible,  indeed,  to  enter  here  into  anyTengt^y  comparison  of  the 
new  conception  and  place  of  theology  with  the  old.  But  the  essential 
nature  of  the  difference  may  be  very  briefly  indicated : 

Just  as,  upon  the  highest  conception  of  the  matter,  religion  arises 
from  the  practical  passion  after  God,  so  theology  arises  from  the 

40 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

intellectual  passion  after  God.  But  the  knowledge  of  God  means  all 
knowledge;  to  know  God  means  also  to  know  the  world;  unless  you 
are  a  Mystic,  there  is  no  such  thing  for  you  as  a  knowledge  of  God 
which  is  not  also  science  of  the  world.  And  if  you  urge  that  with 
you  theology  is  less  proud,  and  renounces  so  high  an  endeavour ;  that 
the  one  thing  you  are  intent  upon  is  the  salvation  of  the  soul;  that 
your  one  function  as  a  theologian  is  to  cast  intellectual  light  upon 
the  course  of  that  salvation  and  thus,  even  though  it  be  indirectly, 
to  assist  in  it : — your  new  definition  of  your  science  still  does  not  free 
you  from  the  obligation  to  walk  in  its  greater  way.  For  what  is  the 
salvation  of  the  soul  ?  That  question  you  can  answer  only  by  raising 
another:  What  is  the  soul?  What  the  salvation  of  the  soul  is, 
depends  on  what  the  soul  itself  is;  unless  you  know  what  the  soul  is, 
you  do  not  know  either  what  its  salvation  properly  consists  in,  or  how 
wide  the  scope  of  that  salvation  is.  But  if  you  would  know  what 
the  soul  is,  you  are  brought  by  a  double  road  to  a  demand  for  the 
knowledge  of  God.  First,  to  know  what  the  soul  is,  you  must 
know  the  true  nature  of  the  world,  of  which  the  soul  is  a  part,  and 
in  whose  order  and  conditions  the  soul  lives  its  life  and  has  its  place 
to  fill ;  and  thus  to  know  the  world  you  must  know  God  whose  char 
acter  is  the  ultimate  character  of  the  world,  and  whose  purpose  is 
the  ultimate  law  of  its  order.  Secondly,  and  directly,  if  you  would 
know  what  the  soul  is,  you  must  apprehend  the  nature  of  its  source, 
that  is,  of  God,  and  the  nature  of  the  end  for  which  He  made  it,  the 
attaining  of  which  is  its  salvation.  So  that  theology,  in  order  to  be 
a  wisdom  of  salvation,  must  be  a  wisdom  of  the  soul,  a  wisdom  of  the 
world,  a  wisdom  of  God.  And  the  scientific  or  constructive  order  of 
these  should  be  noted.  Whether  the  first  and  impelling  interest  of 
the  theologian  is  in  the  soul  or  in  God,  that  which  is  first  in  the  order 
of  scientific  construction  is  God.  In  anything  which  is  to  be  a 
"system"  of  theology,  the  knowledge  of  God — that  is  to  say,  the 
theistic  view  of  the  world — must  stand  as  the  prius  of  the  knowledge 
of  salvation.  Unless  theology  is  to  be  blind,  unless  it  is  to  build  its 
upper  structure  without  giving  any  attention  to  its  foundations,  it 
must  begin  by  working  out,  with  all  the  completeness  possible  to  such 
an  intellect  as  man's,  the  theistic  view  of  the  world;  and  in  its  sub- 

41 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

sequent  work,  soteriology  or  eschatology,  it  must  take  up  no  positions 
inconsistent  with  the  principles  of  that  theistic  view.  Whichever 
interest,  then,  sets  us  upon  the  work  of  theology,  with  whichever  con 
ception  of  it  we  approach  it,  we  are  brought,  first  or  last,  to  the  fact 
that,  in  order  to  discharge  any  of  its  functions,  it  must  be  that  highest 
and  final  science  which  is  at  once  a  wisdom  of  God  and  of  the  world — 
of  God  as  realising  His  purpose  in  and  through  the  history  of  the 
world;  of  the  world  as  at  once  the  scene  and  the  process  of  a  divine 
activity. 

It  is  in  this  regard  that  theology  upon  the  medieval  conception 
of  it,  and  modern  professional  theology,  are  essentially  diverse.     The 
view  which  mediaeval  theologians  took  of  their  work  approximated 
to  that  just  described.     Hence  they  were  profoundly  in  earnest  about 
the  theistic  view  of  the  world.     They  may  not  have  succeeded — per 
haps  no  man  can  succeed — in  working  out  such  a  view  consistently; 
but  at  any  rate  the  attempt  was  made  as  the  first  and  fundamental 
labour  of  theology,  and  to  it  was  devoted  the  whole  energy  of  one  of 
the  greatest  of  intellectual  generations.     By  one  and  the  same  inten 
tion  their  theology  was  a  wisdom  of  God  and  a  wisdom  of  the  universe. 
'  But  modern  systematic  theology,  at  the  time  when  the  sciences  of 
nature  were  beginning  to  dominate  the    intellectual  field,  was    dis 
tinguished  by  nothing  more  than  by  a  great  timidity  about  the  theistic 
view  of  the  world;  nothing  was  farther  from  its  thoughts  than  to  be 
a  wisdom  of  the  universe.     How  anything  so  contrary  to  nature  as 
this — for  theology  afraid  of  theism  is  like  mathematics  afraid  of  being 
mathematical — could  come  to  be,  is  a  long  story  the  main  outlines 
of  which  are  easily  traceable  by  the  student  but  cannot  except  in  a 
brief  reference  be  noted  here.     In  broad  terms,  the  change  was  simply 
a  part  of  the  general  and  inevitable  breaking  up  of  the  mediaeval    • 
unity  of  thought  and  life.     Theology  became  separated,  on  the  one 
side  from  metaphysic  and  from  the  metaphysical  mind,  on  the  other 
from  the  special  sciences.     And  that  meant  that  it  lost  from  both 
sides  its  capacity  for  discharging  its  older  function — its  function  of 
receiving  scientific  knowledge  and  giving  it  its  divine  interpretation. 
And  then  too,  this  tendency  of  theology  to  become  a  smaller  thing 
both  in  its  intellectual  soul  and  in  its  outward  extent,  was  fostered 

42 


AND  THE  VISION  OF  GOD. 

by  another  aspect  of  modern  life — the  dividedness  of  the  church. 
Theology  no  longer  had  "  centre  everywhere."  In  some  of  the 
churches  "  systematic  theology  "  fell  into  the  background  altogether, 
the  institution  preferring  to  stand  in  its  own  living  and  continuous 
strength.  While,  where  it  did  survive,  it  was  usually  with  an  unhappy 
procedure.  Instead  of  seeking  first  the  knowledge  of  God,'  and  then 
basing  upon  that  its  account  of  salvation,  it  came  more  and  more  to 
have  as  its  centre  of  gravity,  came  more  and  more  to  be  "  built 
around,"  a  certain  forensic  scheme  of  soteriology.  That  scheme,  as 
a  matter  of  historical  fact,  was  not  fairly  drawn  from  any  of  the 
chief  theological  sources.  It  had  almost  no  connexion  with  the  actual 
mind  of  Jesus  as  shown  in  the  Evangelia.  It  did  no  justice  to  St. 
Paul's  great  philosophy  of  the  world  and  of  history,  which  centres 
in  the  views  (1)  that  the  supreme  principle  of  the  order  of  the  uni 
verse  is  the  eternal  Christ — in  Christ  the  universe  consists — and  (2) 
that  God's  attitude  toward  man,  as  revealed  in  Christ,  is  one  of  grace/ 
not  of  that  requirement  of  legal  satisfaction  for  wrong  done  which  is 
the  exact  opposite  of  grace.  It  stood  at  an  unspeakable  remove  from 
St.  John's  view  of  Jesus — that  He  is  the  Word  in  whom  the  character 
of  the  Father  and  His  attitude  toward  men  and  the  world  stand 
revealed ;  that,  in  other  words,  He  came  into  the  world  not  to  change 
the  Father's  attitude  toward  men,  but  came  because  of  it  and  to  reveal 
it.  Eather  it  had  arisen  under  the  influence  of  Eoman  Law  and  of 
the  Eoman  legal  and  political  mind  (with  Jewish  law  in  the  back 
ground),  and  had  been  fostered  in  the  West  by  ideas  and  procedures 
belonging  to  the  primitive  jurisprudence  of  the  Germanic  peoples. 
But  though  so  largely  heathen  in  its  origin,  it  had  come  to  be  regarded 
as  Christian  because  it  was  so  tenaciously  held  by  Christians,  and 
because  it  could  be  supported  by  a  careful  selection  of  passages  from 
St.  Paul.  For  the  men  in  question,  this  forensic  scheme  of  soteriology 
was  theology;  and  anything  beyond  it  they  were  inclined  to  dread. 
Of  necessity  they  called  themselves  theists;  but,  while  they  could  be 
severe  upon  those  who  were  not  called  by  that  name,  there  was 
nothing  from  which  they  shrank  with  a  deeper  repugnance  than  the 
bringing  out  into  clear  light  of  the  meaning  and  the  implications  of 
the  theistic  view  of  the  world.  But  precisely  that  theistic  view  it  was 

43 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

which,  seriously  held  and  seriously  developed,  would  have  enabled 
them  to  receive  the  new  knowledge  of  nature  and  to  make  it  at  home 
as  part  of  the  knowledge  of  God.  For  what  the  intelligent  theist 
knows  is  precisely  this:  that  just  because  God  dwells  in  eternity,  He 
is  the  informing  spirit,  the  home  and  the  goal,  of  the  world  that  now 
is;  that  of  Him  the  natural  order  is  a  visible  Word,  and  therefore 
the  study  of  nature  the  study  of  a  part  of  his  thought;  that  in  the 
actual  history  of  yesterday  and  to-day  and  to-morrow  He  is  at  work 
realising  an  eternal  purpose,  and  through  a  thousand  channels  is  call 
ing  upon  men  to  work  along  with  Him;  that  He  is  the  nearest  of 
all  things  to  each  man's  heart,  seeking  to  win  each  man's  heart  to 
Himself  and  to  become  its  supreme  principle  and  central  energy— 
the  Father,  in  a  thousand  ways  and  by  a  thousand  appeals  seeking  to 
win  the  hearts  of  His  prodigal  children  back  to  Himself  and  to 
engage  them  in  the  great  works  at  which  He  Himself  is  working. 
Such  theism,  however,  they  could  not  enter  upon,  much  less  develop 
into  clear  articulation  as  a  view  of  nature  and  of  history.  It  lay  too 
far  from  that  with  which  their  minds  were  filled — the  view  of  the 
universe  as  a  court  of  law;  of  the  divine  administration  of  the  uni 
verse  as  consisting  in  the  transactions  and  expedients  of  such  a  court; 
of  the  death  of  Jesus  as  central  in  those  transactions,  greatest  among 
those  expedients. 

As  was  said  before,  the  question  is  one  of  fact,  not  one  of  fault. 
Perhaps  (though  few  nowadays  care  to  believe  it)  it  is  well  for  us, 
when  we  study  history,  to  carry  our  hearts — our  humanity,  not  our 
partisanship — back  with  us  to  the  bygone  struggles,  and  mourn  for 
the  mistakes  of  the  dead  as  for  our  own  sins.  But  however  that  be, 
one  thing  is  clear:  we  ought,  in  dealing  with  the  past,  to  turn  as 
much  as  possible  from  the  easy  work  of  fault-finding  to  the  more 
difficult  but  more  honourable  task  of  seeking  to  trace  a  wisdom  of  the 
ages  at  work  through  all  the  apparent  confusion  and  wrong.  And 
this  is  specially  important  in  dealing  with  the  present  point.  For, 
as  was  noted  a  moment  ago,  the  modern  disintegration  of  theology  was 
part  of  the  general  modern  disintegration  of  the  mediaeval  unity  of 
thought  and  of  life.  And  that  deep  and  far-reaching  disintegration 
may  in  the  end  have  a  good  result;  the  "hidden  wisdom  of  the 

44 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

world,"  in  whose  service  all  the  generations  stand — even  those  which 
"know  it  not" — may  be,  or  rather  must  be,  at  work  in  it.  Indeed, 
some  at  least  of  the  signs  of  this  have  long  been  visible.  Many  of  the 
sundered  factors,  forced  to  stand  alone — each  erected  into  a  solitary 
kingdom,  and  compelled  to  find  a  whole  world  in  itself  in  order  to 
live  at  all — have  entered  into  deeper  possession  of  themselves  and  of 
their  own  resources;  science,  for  instance,  ceasing  for  a  time  to  look 
upon  God,  has  entered  with  a  new  freedom  and  a  new  fulness  upon  the 
mastery  of  nature;  while  literature,  with  new  powers  of  sympathy 
and  passion  and  insight,  has  recovered  and  has  glorified  whole  regions 
of  the  soul  that  long  had  lain  in  neglect.  And  of  this  enriching  and 
deepening  of  life  in  its  estranged  and  severed  aspects,  the  result  is 
that  if  a  new  integration  of  thought  and  of  life — a  new  intellectual 
and  social  integration — should  in  any  future  be  achieved,  it  would 
be  one  vastly  richer  than  the  mediaeval.  All  those  powers  of  human 
nature — industrial,  commercial,  political,  literary,  scientific,  humani 
tarian — that  have  swung  away  from  religion,  will  be  seen  to  have 
swung  out  in  a  great  circle  which  at  last  will  bring  man  back,  with 
wider  life  and  larger  heart,  to  God.  Such  a  synthesis,  indeed,  does 
seem  to  be  drawing  nearer  on  the  intellectual  side ;  being  aided,  from 
the  one  direction,  by  the  Idealistic  interpretation  of  science ;  and  from 
the  other  direction,  by  the  historical  study  of  the  Bible — a  study 
which,  by  setting  the  mind  of  Christ  in  its  place  of  supremacy,  makes 
it  possible  for  virtually  every  genuine  power  of  human  nature  and  of 
the  world  to  reconcile  itself  to  God  and  find  its  fitting  place  and  its 
true  being  in  the  one  world-work  of  God.  But  on  the  social  side,  if 
one  confine  one's  self  to  actual  achievement  as  distinct  from  beliefs 
and  ideals,  one  has  to  say  that  the  struggle  is  as  yet  more  in  evidence 
than  the  synthesis;  in  some  regards,  indeed,  though  happily  not  in 
all,  the  gulfs  between  class  and  class,  interest  and  interest,  seem,  if 
possible,  to  be  growing  deeper. 

But  we  must  return  to  the  special  point  here  in  question.  Whether 
the  fact  be  regarded  with  hope  and  therefore  resolutely  accepted  and 
even  welcomed,  or  whether  it  be  judged  with  grief  and  anger,  the  fact 
itself  remains  that  when,  through  the  triumphant  advance  of  the 
scientific  point  of  view,  the  time  of  intellectual  crisis  came  to  modern 

45 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

men,  the  theologians  had  neither  the  requisite  equipment  of  ideas,  nor 
the  requisite  intellectual  vision  of  God,  to  enable  them  to  perform  the 
function  which  at  such  a  time  they  owe  the  world.  It  was  not  in 
them  to  receive  the  modern  scientific  movement,  to  view  its  results 
sub  specie  quadam  aeternitatis,  and  thus  to  give  them,  so  far  as  is 
possible  to  the  human  intellect,  their  "  divine  interpretation."  In 
this  situation  some  of  us  were  able  to  trust  stubbornly  to  our  own 
hearts  and  to  the  religion  from  which  our  fathers  had  drawn  their 
heroic  strength;  and  so  were  able  to  steer  straight  on  through  the 
intellectual  chaos.  Others  of  us,  who  could  not  rest  in  a  division  of 
the  heart  from  the  intelligence,  obeyed  an  inward  call  and  made  a 
journey — perilous  and  beneficent,  as  all  true  journeys  are — to  far-off 
schools;  and  there;  from  the  Kantians  or  from  Plato,  gained  the 
insights  to  which  those  who  taught  us  with  authority  ought  to  have 
brought  us.  But  those  are  exceptional  cases.  The  important  thing 
is  to  notice  the  effect  upon  the  general  modern  mind.  It  came  to 
this:  that  when  men  of  science,  whose,  work  compelled  us  to  respect 
them,  drew  from  their  indisputable  acquaintance  with  nature  the  con 
clusion  that  the  religious  view  of  man  and  of  life  and  of  the  world  could 
no  longer  stand,  we  were  in  a  position  where  we  could  not  fairly  resist 
them;  in  a  sense  their  battle  was  won  before  they  began  the  attack. 
For,  in  so  far  as  the  most  of  us  had  a  reasoned  view  of  the  world  at 
all,  a  reasoned  outlook  upon  the  nature  and  structure  of  the  cosmos 
in  which  we  live,  a  reasoned  apprehension  of  the  character  of  that 
continuity  which  runs  like  fate  through  its  entire  history  and  all  its 
processes,  it  was  precisely  from  those  men  of  science  that  we  had 
received  it.  Who  else  was  there  to  give  it  to  us?  And  that  was  not 
all.  We  not  only  received  it  from  them,  but  we  received  it  in. their 
sense,  and  from  the  point  of  view  of  their  sciences ;  for  there  was  no 
higher  interpretation  which  showed  a  genuinely  scientific  spirit  and 
could  therefore  be  convincing  to  an  age  of  scientific  mind.1 

i  The  wisdom  which  leads  on  the  ages  is  greater  than  our  dreams,  and  we  may  trust 
that  even  in  its  sternness  it  is  kindlier  than  our  fairest  imaginations ;  else  it  might  be 
permissible  for  a  man  to  dream  how  well  it  would  have  been  for  us  all,  if,  in  the  day  when 
the  sciences  of  nature  were  coming  forward,  those  who  guided  the  thought  of  the  church 
had  been  men  of  Origen's  spirit. 

46 


AND    THE   VISION    OF    GOD 

(ft) 

But  if  in  the  realm  of  thought  there  has  come  to  be  a  gulf  between 
the  science  that  knows  the  earth  and  the  faith  that  looks  to  heaven, 
much  more  does  the  separation  of  earth  and  heaven  find  place  in  the 
practical  conduct  of  life.  There  is  to  be  found  the  true  "  modern 
Materialism."  We  have  become  materialised  in  our  ambitions  and 
ideals;  the  ultimate  and  controlling  purpose  of  life  is  too  little  the 
promotion  of  a  good  which  is  eternal  and  common  to  all,  too  much 
the  attaining  of  that  material  good  which  passes  rapidly  away  and  the 
possession  of  which  by  one  man  frequently  involves  the  exclusion  of 
others  from  it.  To  state  the  case  more  broadly,  we  have  fallen  into 
bondage  to  what  older  men  were  wont  to  call  "  the  spirit  of  the 
world" — the  spirit  which  always  is  individualistic  and  selfish,  and 
usually  is  earthly  and  mercenary.  It  was  pointed  out  above  that 
mediaeval  religion,  precisely  because  it  set  men  high  above  the  earth, 
gave  them  a  spirit  of  comprehensive  unity  in  dealing  with  the  things 
of  the  earth;  led  them  to  the  idea  of  the  unity,  in  a  divine  order,  of 
the  whole  social  organisation  of  life.  But  the  spirit  of  the  world 
exerts  just  the  opposite  influence.  It  begins  by  setting  each  man 
upon  the  search  after  his  own  individual  good;  and  ends  by  leaving 
him  incapable  of  devoting  himself  to  any  good  save  that  which  is 
earthly  and  material. 

One  of  the  instances  of  this  dominance  of  practical  materialism 
and  of  the  spirit  of  the  world — the  instance  that  must  stand  here  as 
representative  of  all  the  rest — is  perhaps  the  saddest  thing  in  modern 
life.  Because  the  leaders  of  modern  industrial  society  make  material^ 
interests  supreme  in  their  lives,  great  masses  of  other  men  are  com 
pelled  to  make  material  considerations,  in  their  most  elementary  and 
most  brutal  form,  supreme  in  their  lives.  For  while  the  modern 
manner  of  living  is  more  humane  than  the  mediaeval,  yet,  in  the 
modern  industrial  organisation  of  society,  the  gaining  of  the  liveli 
hood  itself  is,  for  whole  classes  of  the  people,  a  harder,  a  more  pre 
carious,  in  many  cases  a  more  absolutely  hopeless,  matter  than  it  was 
in  mediaeval  society,  and  precisely  for  that  reason  claims  all  the 
energies  of  life,  leaving  none  for  higher  things. 

47 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

Such  the  modern  position  has  come  to  be.  In  the  realm  of 
thought,  indeed,  as  already  has  been  indicated,  the  last  quarter  of  a 
century  has  brought  a  great  improvement.  We  are  looking  with  wiser 
eyes  upon  the  sciences  of  nature — because  we  ourselves  have  become 
more  scientific;  and  because,  in  growing  more  scientific,  we  have 
found  that  the  spirit  of  Christ  and  the  spirit  of  science  go  naturally 
together,  like  love  and  light.  In  that  sense,  the  first  intensity  of  the 
intellectual  conflict  is  past.  And  one  of  the  signs  of  this  calls  for 
special  notice.  Of  the  ways  in  which  the  mind  of  the  church  has 
become  more  scientific,  and  in  becoming  so  has  apprehended  the  kin 
ship  of  the  spirit  of  Christ  and  the  spirit  of  science,  the  most  impor 
tant  (leaving  aside  the  general  fact  of  an  increasing  spaciousness  in 
thought  and  therefore  in  intellectual  sympathy)  lies  in  the  growth 
of  that  scientific  study  known  as  Biblical  Theology.  Biblical  Theol 
ogy  arose  when  the  scientific  spirit,  by  its  own  natural  and  legitimate 
advance,  entered  into  the  church  and  took  possession  of  the  key  to  the 
whole  theological  situation — namely,  of  the  sources.  And  this  means 
that  it  is  from  the  scientific  spirit  that  modern  theology  has  received 
its  greatest  benefaction — the  restoration  to  it  of  Christ  as  He  actually 
was,  and  of  His  mind  as  it  actually  was  manifested.  It  is  a  thing 
full  of  hope  for  both  the  church  and  the  world  that  in  theology  the 
dominance  of  invented  systems  with  their  proof-texts — systems  which 
were  the  expressions  and  the  symbols  of  schools,  and  sects,  and  par 
ties,  or  even  of  individuals — is  slowly  passing  away,  and  the  mind 
of  Jesus,  as  gathered  from  His  recorded  teaching  and  action,  and 
from  the  Christian  consciousness,  is  more  and  more  becoming 
determinative.1 

But  while  the  first  intensity  of  the  conflict  is  thus  past  on  the 
intellectual  side,  the  conflict  itself  is  not  yet  over.  Not  only  for  many 
individual  minds,  thinking  honestly  their  own  thoughts  and  seeking  as 
best  they  can  the  light  necessary  to  life,  but  also  for  many  influential 
groups  of  teachers  and  of  learners,  the  two  sides  are  still  in  antithesis. 
On  the  one  side  religion,  not  by  any  commendation  of  the  theologians 

i  In  all  such  discussions  concerning  theology  and  the  mind  which  is  desirable  as  the 
mind  of  the  chairch,  it  is  of  course  to  be  remembered  that,  important  as  theology  is,  it  is 
not  the  supreme  thing ;  the  chosen  dwelling-place  of  the  spirit  of  Christ  always  has  been, 
always  will  be,  in  pure  and  simple  hearts  which  love  Him  and  live  in  that  love. 

48 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

but  by  intrinsic  power  of  its  own,  makes  still  the  appeal  which  twice 
at  least  has  mastered  the  world;  and  the  former  wisdom,  the  wisdom 
mediaeval  and  Platonic,  whose  knowledge  was  of  the  soul  and  whose 
vision  was  of  the  home  of  the  soul,  finds  still  to  be  its  prophets  men 
over  whom  the  spirit  of  the  time  has  no  dominion,  a  Wordsworth  or 
a  Newman.  But  on  the  other  side  the  scientific  mind  and  the  science 
which  is  its  work  stand  over  against  religion  and  over  against  the 
older  wisdom  as  unreconciled  powers,  equally  resolute,  equally  mas 
terful,  and  to  many  minds  greater  in  power  of  immediate  and  con 
vincing  verification.  It  is  a  great  conflict;  and  yet  it  is  the  lesser 
half  of  the  spiritual  struggle  into  which  every  modern  man  is  born; 
over  against  it  stands  its  greater  counterpart,  the  conflict  in  the  realm 
of  practice,  where,  in  opposition  to  the  spirit  of  the  cross,  there  stand 
the  spirit  of  the  world,  and  that  far-reaching  materialisation  of  life 
which  the  spirit  of  the  world,  working  with  mightier  instruments  than 
ever  before,  has  effected. 

III. 

Men  who  are  in  earnest  about  their  citizenship  in  the  world,  when 
they  find  themselves  in  the  thick  of  the  struggle  just  referred  to, 
soon  learn  one  thing :  the  only  power  that  can  overcome  the  spirit  of 
the  world  is  something  as  practical  as  itself;  is  the  spirit  which  has 
seen  and  chosen  the  better  part,  and  lives  in  the  world  "not  to  be 
ministered  unto,  but  to  minister  " — the  spirit  of  those  who  have  looked 
upon  their  Lord  and  serve  Him  by  more  than  speech.  So  that  the 
only  value  that  can  be  ascribed  to  discussion  and  argument  is  a  sec-\' 
ondary  value.  But  that  value,  though  secondary,  is  by  no  means 
slight.  For  we  must  remember  that  thought  and  practice  do  not 
stand  apart;  they  are  related  as  soul  and  body.  And  in  particular, 
the  practical  spirit  of  religion  needs  clear  eyes.  There  is  no 
religion — no  religion  such  as  can  change  the  world — without  vision; 
to  choose  the  better  part  men  must  look  beyond  the  earth  and  apprehend 
heavenly  realities.  And  though  such  apprehension  need  not  be  dis 
tinctly  intellectual  in  form,  yet,  in  at  least  some  of  the  members  of 
every  society,  it  ought  to  rise  to  the  form  of  that  penetrating  and 

5  49 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

systematic  thought  which  is  able  to  look  upon  the  world  and  assure 
itself  what  the  reality  of  the  world  actually  is — whether  it  is  a  mate 
rialistic  or  a  spiritual  order,  whether  it  is  good,  or  simply  indifferent 
to  good,  or  an  eternal  dualism  of  good  and  evil.  And  what  has 
already  been  said  will  show  that  in  our  day  the  problem  for  such 
thought — the  problem  for  "  philosophy  "•  —has  been  brought  to  a  very 
pointed  form :  What  is  the  ultimate  meaning  for  life  and  religion  of 
scientific  knowledge  of  nature? 
To  the  apparent  conflict,  then,  between  the  science  which  knows 
nature  and  the  religion  which  has  as  its  inner  impulse  a  vision  of 
God,  we  must  now  turn.  The  first  thing  to  be  noticed  is  that  such 
a  conflict  is  scarcely  a  case  of  truth  against  falsehood.  It  is  rather 
a  case  of  divided  knowledge  and  divided  insight;  a  case  of  truth 
against  truth.  Men  placed  in  such  circumstances  are  sure  to  have 
recourse  to  many  "  working  solutions  " ;  to  the  faith  that  dares,  or 
to  the  stubborn  manliness  that  clings  to  ancient  morality  or  religion 
in  spite  of  intellectual  confusion.  These  are  measures  of  war, 
inevitable  upon  an  obscure  and  troubled  battlefield ;  and  the  men  who 
adopt  them  often  serve  greatly  their  day  and  society.  But  the  fact 
remains  that  such  attitudes  afe  not  adequate  solutions.  And  what  is 
necessary  to  such  an  adequate  solution  is  equally  clear.  In  a  division 
of  the  sort  now  in  question,  where  one  side  is  based  upon  a  certain 
order  of  science,  the  only  solution  which  can  be  finally  satisfactory 
consists  in  more  or  higher  science;  consists,  that  is  to  say,  in  gaining 
by  a  genuinely  scientific  method  a  point  of  view  high  enough  to  give 
a  comprehensive  outlook  over  both  the  warring  sides  and  over  the 
territory  upon  which  their  warfare  is  waged.  For  it  is  unjust  to 
take  your  stand  within  one  side,  as  within  a  closed  circle,  and  then 
from  within  that  closed  circle  to  pass  judgment  upon  positions  which 
lie  outside  and  are  based  upon  a  different  order  of  principles.  That 
is  to  say,  it  is  unjust  to  take  one's  stand  within  the  "  natural  science 
consciousness  "  and  in  its  name  summarily  to  brush  aside  the  con 
sciousness  of  which  Wordsworth  is  in  one  way,  and  Newman  in  another 
way,  a  type.  And  it  is  equally  unjust  to  call  for  the  flat  supersession 
of  the  scientific  consciousness,  on  the  ground  that  some  other  con 
sciousness—poetic,  moral,  religious— has  the  right  of  way.  Neither 

50 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

of  these  procedures  constitutes  a  solution  of  the  problem.  In  neither 
can  a  thoughtful  and  honest  mind  rest  permanently  or  take  up  its 
ultimate  abode.  The  first  is  the  hasty — occasionally  the  contemp 
tuous — evasion  of  the  problem  by  refusing  to  recognise  the  existence 
and  weight  of  one  of  the  two  sides ;  and  such  a  procedure  contradicts 
that  very  spirit  of  science  in  the  name  of  which  it  is  undertaken. 
The  second  is  the  makeshift  of  spiritual  desperation.1  By  this  it  is 
riot  meant  that  poetic  intuition  and  religious  vision  have  no  place  in 
man's  life.  On  the  contrary,  his  ordinary  life  in  its  whole  range  of 
daily  thought  and  daily  work,  is  a  pitiable  thing  without  them.  And 
even  in  conflicts  such  as  are  here  in  question,  men  have  more  than 
once  or  twice  done  great  and  genuine  service  by  taking  their  stand 
upon  poetic  intuition  and  religious  vision,  and  in  their  name  defying 
both  the  scientific  and  the  commercial  consciousness.  How  this  can 
be  so,  we  shall  a  little  farther  on  be  in  better  position  to  see.  In  the 
meantime,  what  we  have  to  notice  is  that  such  an  attitude  is  not  a 
permanent  solution.  To  settle  down  permanently  into^uch  an  atti 
tude — worse  still,  to  speak  authoritatively  to  the  thinking  men  of 
your  generation  and  have  nothing  but  such  an  attitude  to  commend 
to  them — is  simply  to  set  one  closed  circle  against  another  closed 
circle;  is  simply  to  solidify  the  opposed  ranks  in  their  opposition. 
What  is  required  for  a  permanent  solution  is  that  the  critical  and  /* 
disinterested  reason,  walking  in  the  way  of  science  and  in  the  spirit 
of  science,  should  strive  forward  toward  its  goal;  that  is  to  say, 
toward  a  view  of  the  world  as  one.  Such  a  view,  if  only  it  could  be 
gained  (and — as  we  shall  see — it  can  be  gained)  would  enable  us  to 
do  both  of  the  things  which  are  necessary  to  an  adequate  solution.  It 
would  enable  us,  first,  to  recognise  whatever  truth  there  may  be  on 
each  side;  nay,  to  do  more,  to  give  that  truth  a  deeper  meaning  and 
a  fuller  interpretation  by  setting  it  in  its  place  in  a  system  of  wider 
truth.  And  how  much  this  latter  consideration  means  may  be  seen 
by  remembering  one  thing :  if  each  side  has  its  truth,  if  loth  of  the 
opposed  sides  are  really  elements  in  one  truth  and  one  life,  each  having 

i  And  when  employed  as  a  method  of  theology,  is  something  worse ;  is  a  makeshift  of 
desperation  on  the  part  of  men  who  ought  to  be  the  masters  and  kings  of  the  whole  V 
intellectual  situation,  but  have  allowed  themselves  to  be  driven  to  bay  in  a  corner  of  their 
own  realm. 

51 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

its  own  great  place  and  great  right,  then  we  may  be  sure  that  each 
can  also  contribute  to  the  power  and  breadth  of  the  other;  for  great 
truths  are  not  self-contained;  they  answer  to  one  another  and  con 
tribute  to  one  another.  Secondly,  it  would  enable  us  to  understand 
the  limitations  under  which  each  of  the  sides  apprehended  and 
envisaged  its  own  truth — limitations  which  shut  each  side  away  from 
the  other  and  made  each  accuse  the  other  of  blindness  or  even  of 
falsehood.  And  understanding  these  limitations  means  (as  Hegel  so 
steadily  insisted)  a  very  great  deal  more  than  merely  stating  the 
fact  of  their  existence.  It  means  understanding  how  they  came  to 
be;  how  they  are  inevitably  bound  up  with  certain  special  points  of 
view,  so  that  the  men  who  live  habitually  at  these  points  of  view  are 
subject  to  the  corresponding  limitations  of  outlook  upon  the  world. 
Such  a  method  would  enable  us  to  recognise  truth  wherever  there  is 
truth  to  be  recognised;  and  not  merely  to  recognise  it,  but  (what  is 
more  difficult)  to  do  justice  to  it.  In  particular  it  would  enable  us 
to  leave  the  established  laws  and  principles  of  natural  and  physical 
science  standing  in  .their  full  inner  integrity  and  at  the  same  time 
to  take  them  up  as  harmonious  elements  in  a  system  of  truth  wider 
than  themselves;  a  system  in  whose  wider  light  their  ultimate  sig 
nificance  for  life  and  for  the  meaning  of  life  would  become  manifest. 
And  that  would  put  us  in  position  to  correct  precisely  the  order  of 
mistakes  with  which  we  are  here  concerned;  not  mistakes  in  matters 
of  fact  (a  sort  of  mistakes  which  scientific  men  are  not  given  to 
making)  ;  but  mistakes  in  interpretation,  mistakes  in  applying  the 
principles  and  the  points  of  view  of  the  special  sciences  to  life  and  to 
the  problem  of  the  meaning  of  life. 

Indeed,  the  demand  for  such  a  solution  might  be  stated  wholly 
from  the  side  of  science  itself.  For  it  is  the  presupposition  of  all 
science  and  of  all  endeavour  after  science — it  is  the  presupposition  of 
every  step  in  every  scientific  investigation— that  the  world  is  one,  a 
single  system  of  interrelated  facts;  and  that  therefore  knowledge  is 
one,  a  single  system  of  related  insights.  Hence  the  ultimate  truth 
about  any  one  part  of  the  world,  or  about  the  scientific  principles 
employed  in  the  study  of  it,  becomes  manifest  only  from  the  centre ; 
only  from  a  point  of  view  which  commands  the  whole  field  and  which 

52 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

is  gained,  not  so  much  by  the  study  of  fact  after  fact  in  detail  as  by 
apprehending  the  inner  nature  of  the  total  system.  And  it  is  pre 
cisely  when  truths  appear  to  conflict  that  it  is  most  important  to 
remember  this;  most  important  of  all  when  the  conflict  is  such  as 
that  between  the  "natural  science  consciousness"  and  the  religious 
consciousness,  where  the  two  sides  appear  to  stand  so  far  apart,  and 
yet  each  is  so  deeply  rooted  in  existing  reality. 

The  task,  then,  which  faces  the  man  who  has  taken  into  his  heart 
that  for  which  Wordsworth  and  Newman  stand,  and  who  at  the  same 
time  finds  himself  compelled  whether  he  will  or  no  to  be  an  intel 
lectual  citizen  of  the  modern  world,  may  be  summed  up  thus. — First 
he  has  to  attempt  to  comprehend  the  ultimate  significance  for  the  v 
problem  of  the  meaning  of  life,  of  the  modern  scientific  knowledge 
of  nature.  Secondly,  to  do  this  he  must  seek  to  gain  a  point  of  view 
from  which,  in  some  genuine  sense  of  the  words,  the  world  can  be 
seen  as  one,  life  viewed  as  a  whole,  facts  comprehended  sub  specie 
quadam  aeternitatis.  Thirdly,  the  quest  of  that  point  of  view  must  v 
be  carried  on  in  a  genuinely  scientific  temper.  Rebuke  of  science; 
evasion  of  the  demands  of  the  scientific  spirit ;  the  "  flat  supersession 
of  the  scientific  consciousness  "  in  the  name  of  the  religious  conscious 
ness  ;  the  attempt  to  follow  some  by-path  or  "short  cut "  upon  which 
one  hopes  to  get  past  the  scientific  position  without  the  danger  of 
being  taken  prisoner : — all  these  are  ab  initio  forbidden.1  In  a  word, 

i  One  of  these  attempts  to  "get  past  the  scientific  position  "  is  so  fundamentally  bad 
as  to  deserve  special  mention— the  endeavour  to  justify  belief  in  God  by  seeking  to  find 
gaps  in  the  continuity  of  nature.  It  is  true  that  a  God  thus  made  manifest— made  mani 
fest  not  by  the  greatness  and  harmony  of  nature,  not  by  its  abiding  law  and  continuous 
order,  but  by  its  rents  and  gaps— would  be  no  worthy  object  of  religious  devotion.  But 
that  is  only  the  beginning  of  the  matter.  Once  you  shatter  the  continuity  of  nature,  you 
shatter  Imore  than  Materialism.  You  shatter  the  possibility  of  all  science  whatever. 
You  open  up  the  gulf  of  universal  scepticism,  and  Materialism  disappears  in  it,  it  is  true, 
but  along  with  it  disappear  Theism  and  theology  and  the  rational  basis  for  every  sort  of 
religion  except  two,  between  which  men  will  continue  to  choose  according  to  their 
individual  dispositions— Stoicism  (as  a  practical  temper,  not  as  a  philosophy)  and 
Epicureanism. 

In  a  word,  in  insisting  upon  the  continuity  of  nature,  men  of  science  have  been  better 
theologians  than  the  theologians  themselves.  If  God  exists  at  all,  He  is  the  God  of  all 
nature  and  of  every  natural  law.  There  are  no  gaps  in  His  workmanship,  no  breaches  of 
continuity  in  His  activity.  All  nature  is  an  activity  of  His,  and  every  natural  law  a 
principle  of  that  activity.  If  the  theologians  would  be  true  to  theology,  what  they  have 
to  do  is  to  protest,  not  against  the  'principle  of  continuity,  but  against  too  narrow  a 
reading  of  it  and  too  narrow  an  application  of  it  to  reality.  The  principle  of  continuity  is 

53 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

the  attempt  to  discover  the  ultimate  significance  for  life  of  our  knowl 
edge  of  nature  should  be  carried  through  with  fidelity  to  the  scientific 
spirit;  and  the  view  finally  gained  of  the  ultimate  meaning  of  our 
science  of  nature  should  be,  in  a  genuine  sense  of  the  words,  a  farther 
stage  of  science  itself. 

IV. 

But  in  approaching  this  task  one  is  approaching  no  new  or  purely 
modern  task.  To  gain  insight  into  the  significance,  for  the  problem 
of  the  meaning  of  life,  of  the  fact  that  man  has  science  of  nature; 
and  so  to  gain  that  insight  that  it  shall  be  a  farther  stage  of  the  same 
science : — upon  this  attempt,  or  upon  a  greater  which  includes  it,  has 
been  directed  the  longest  and  most  continuous  of  all  the  labours  of  the 
human  mind.  Each  intellectual  era  has  come  to  the  problem  in  its 
own  way;  in  its  own  way  has  stated  the  problem,  in  its  own  way 
attempted  the  solution;  and  the  struggle  upward  through  inadequate 
categories  has  been  slow  and  stubborn.  Hence  the  special  pleader  or 
the  hasty  critic  can  easily  arrange  a  clever  argument  for  the  charge 
that  the  imagined  insight  of  each  age  stands  in  contradiction  to  that 
of  the  others,  and  that  therefore  the  wholo  history  establishes  nothing. 
But  as  a  matter  of  fact  that  history  has  the  unity  which  arises  from 
a  central  and  catholic  line  of  development.  And  the  man  who  is 
willing,  and  who  is  able,  by  historical  study,  to  repeat  that  develop 
ment  in  his  own  thinking  and  live  it  over  again  in  his  own  soul— 
the  man  who  illuminates  his  soul  with  the  wisdom  of  the  ages,  and 
grows  into  that  illumination  as  the  ages  themselves  grew  into  it — is 
the  man  who,  when  the  problem  here  at  issue  falls  upon  him,  can 
conduct  most  intelligently  his  own,  wrestle  with  it,  and  can  best  be 
a  guide  to  others. 

For  what  the  great  men  of  thought  who  in  their  succession  con 
stitute  that  "  central  and  catholic  line  "  have  seen,  is  precisely  that 

unworthily  treated  if  it  is  limited  to  certain  physical  and  chemical  processes.  The  true 
field  of  the  principle  of  continuity  is  the  total  history  in  time,  the  total  evolution,  of  the 
universe.  And  as  so  viewed,  it  is  simply  one  way  of  apprehending  the  essential  ration 
ality  of  God  and  of  the  divine  action  in  nature  and  in  history.  In  this— and  I  think  only 
in  this— lies  the  basis  for  a  worthy  constructive  doctrine  of  miracle.  (See  the  acute 
discussion  in  Mr.  Balfour's  Foundations  of  Belief,  1897,  p.  316  seq.) 

54 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

such  a  farther  stage  of  science  as  was  referred  to  above  is  possible. 
And  not  only  that  it  is  possible,  but  also  that  the  human  intellect 
must  seek  after  it  unless  the  human  intellect  is  to  live  in  treason 
against  the  scientific  spirit.  They  have  seen,  in  the  first  place,  that 
man's  knowledge  of  the  material  order  implies  a  greater  whole  of 
knowledge,  from  whose  point  of  view  the  world  is  seen  as  a  whole  and 
man's  life  in  its  true  meaning;  and  in  the  second  place,  that  that 
greater  whole  of  knowledge  is  a  fulfilment  of  man's  knowledge  of 
nature,  not  a  revolt  against  it,  nor  a  contradiction  of  it. 

The  age-long  labour  in  which  the  "  masters  of  them  that  know  " 
endeavoured  to  fulfil  the  scientific  demand  which  they  had  thus  appre 
hended,  cannot,  of  course,  be  described  or  outlined  here.  But  cer 
tain  of  the  outstanding  facts  of  its  history,  if  noted  at  this  point, 
will  enable  us  to  orient  ourselves  in  the  courts  of  philosophy,  and  to 
apprehend  the  nature  of  the  tradition  that  has  grown  up  there.1 

That  tradition*-  entered,  almost  at  its  beginning,  into  conscious 
possession  of  its  own  true  nature  as  an  effort  after  the  unity  of  life. 
For  the  mind  which  gave  rise  to  philosophy  and  science,  and  presided 
over  the  beginnings  of  their  tradition,  and  informed  the  construction 
of  their  first  great  monuments,  was  that  of  the  Greeks;  and  the 
graver  genius  of  that  race-^even  while  its  cities,  by  divisions  without 
and  within,  were  working  out  for  themselves  irremediable  ruin- 
sought  to  rise  above  the  divisions  of  thought  and  of  practice ;  sought 
to  see  life  "  steadily,"  to  see  it  "  whole,"  and  to  discover,  at 
once  for  the  individual  and  the  state,, the  true  unity  of  life.  That 
unity  the  Greek — so  far  as  the  deeper  genius  of  Hellas  prevailed  in  him 
— sought  by  proportion.  He  would  bring  life  to  unity,  not  by 
extirpating  all  interests  save  one — driving  out  religion,  for  instance, 
in  the  name  of  science,  or  the  good  in  the  name  of  the  beautiful,  or 
the  expert  in  government  in  the  name  of  democracy — but  rather  by 

i  For  the  younger  student  of  philosophy,  the  historical  study  that  does  this  has,  in 
addition  to  the  value  noted  earlier  in  the  text,  this  special  value  :  it  puts  him  in  position 
to  make  with  more  intelligence  his  estimate  of  the  present-day  voices  that  claim  hia 
attention.  For  in  this  as  in  every  age,  some  of  the  writers  in  philosophy  are  so  related  to 
the  traditional  development  that  their  own  individual  strength  is  at  once  rooted  in  and 
reinforced  by  the  incalculable  strength  of  the  central  and  catholic  past ;  while  others,  who 
astonish  their  day  with  inventions  of  their  own,  represent  in  philosophy  the  merely 
individual  and  therefore  the  transient. 

55 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

giving  to  each  legitimate  interest  and  capability  of  the  soul,  its  due 
and  proportionate  place — primary  or  secondary,  as  the  case  might  be — 
in  the  single  system  of  an  harmoniously  ordered  life.  The  life 
which  results  when  a  single  limited  interest,  or  a  single  unbridled 
tendency  of  human  nature,  takes  complete  possession  of  a  human 
soul  and  of  a  human  body,  he  refused  to  call  a  human  life;  and 
any  social  order  which  would  make  such  life  inevitable  to  the 
various  classes  of  enfranchised  citizens  he  looked  upon  as  essentially 
vicious.  In  the  state,  according  to  the  ideal  of  it,  each  citizen  was 
to  perform  freely  and  devotedly  the  function  for  which  nature  fitted 
him;  and  so  the  life,  on  the  one  hand  of  the  state,  on  the  other  of 
each  individual  citizen  in  it,  was  to  reach  completeness  both  of 
development  and  of  efficiency.  Unity  of  life;  completeness  of  life; 
and  the  securing  of  these  by  harmonious  co-operation  of  natural  powers 
in  which  each  helps  the  others  by  doing  with  excellence  its  own  work : — 
this  was  at  once  his  ideal  of  life  and  his  principle  for  the  organisation 
of  the  state. 

Furthermore,  the  Greek  mind  in  its  scientific  workmanship  was 
thoroughly  disinterested.  Greek  men  of  science  and  Greek  men  of 
thought  were  wont  to  look  upon  the  facts  of  life  and  the  facts  of  the 
world  with  clear  and  direct  eyes;  they  saw  things  just  as  they  are 
and  described  them  exactly  as  they  found  them.  The  notion  that 
truth — truth  in  the  grave  and  deep  sense  of  the  word — could  have  ill 
consequences  in  the  practical  life,  had  no  place  with  them.  By  the 
very  nature  of  the  mind  in  them  they  were  free  from  the  vice  of  doing 
violence  to  the  scientific  conscience  in  order  to  conduct  special  plead 
ings  for  ethical  and  theological  positions.  Indeed,  it  is  precisely  for 
that  reason  that  the  Greek  mind  has  contributed,  as  to  the  cause  of 
science,  so  also,  and  even  more  profoundly,  to  the  cause  of  goodness. 
For  hostility  to  science,  or  even  alienation  from  it,  in  the  interest  of 
morality  or  religion,  is  as  injurious  to  these  themselves  as  to  science; 
nay,  is  even  more  injurious;  for  it  works  them  a  triple  injury.  It 
exposes  their  fundamental  principles  to  suspicion  as  fearing  the  light. 
It  shatters  the  unity  and  integrity  of  life ;  and  incompleteness  of  life 
means  incompleteness  of  morality  and  of  religion.  And — the  deepest 
injury  of  all — it  steals  away  from  them  that  which  is  at  once  their 

56 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

eyesight,,  their  interpreter,  and  their  intellectual  soul,  and  thus  leaves 
them  to  the  mercy  of  the  dogmatic  and  the  priestly  mind. 

These  qualities  of  the  Greek  spirit  made  the  interpretation  of  life 
which  it  wrought  out  a  thing  of  supreme  value  for  ever  to  the  men 
who,  for  the  business  of  living  life,  wish  to  clear  their  eyes  and  clear 
their  intelligence.  That  interpretation  took  two  main  forms :  a  more 
literary,  in  the  work  of  the  tragedians,  who  in  huge  and  majestic 
symbols  of  ancient  legend  expressed  their  sense  of  the  operation  in 
man's  life  of  a  necessity  greater  than  man,  so  that  the  blind  choices, 
the  hasty  movements  of  the  individual  will,  bring  in  their  train  inex 
orable  fate — fate  clad  always  in  terror,  but  sometimes  dimly  seen  to 
the  poet's  faith  to  be  the  form  of  a  great  righteousness;  and  a  more 
scientific,  in  the  work  of  certain  great  men  of  thought  who  carried 
farther  than  the  poets  the  attempt  to  understand  the  nature  of  that 
necessity,  and  found  it  to  be  eternal,  and,  in  the  highest  sense 
of  the  words,  rational  and  righteous.  By  singular  good  fortune  to 
humanity,  this  latter  interpretation  came  to  share,  at  its  culmination 
in  Plato,  in  one  great  feature  of  the  former :  came  to  add  to  its  own 
intrinsic  value  as  a  guide  of  life  a  manner  of  expression  fitted  to  win 
men's  hearts.  For  while  Plato  had,  in  its  very  highest  form,  the 
disinterested  scientific  temper  of  the  Greeks,  and  their  clearness  of 
intellectual  vision,  he  was  more  than  a  great  scientific  intellect  con 
templating  life.  He  was  one  of  the  most  human  of  men.  He  knew 
life  by  walking  in  its  ways,  by  sharing  in  its  greater  struggles,  by 
enduring  its  greater  sorrows.  Yet  his  vision  was  driven  beyond  the 
horizon  of  this  world;  alike  by  the  discovery  of  his  intellect 
and  by  the  demand  of  his  soul  for  a  home  truly  appropriate  to 
its  nature,  he  was  led  to  contemplate  an  eternity  and  a  perfection, 
which  are  not  of  this  world,  though  they  are  the  truth  of  it  and  the 
standard  for  judging  all  its  affairs.  And  in  this  ascent  of  his  soul 
the  characteristic  genius  of  his  race  did  not  desert  him,  though  its 
lighter  elements  were  rebuked  and  fled.  He  remained  a  Greek  seeking 
for  integrity  of  life  and  delighting  in  the  exercise  of  all  the  faculties 
of  the  soul;  an  artist,  with  the  artist's  instinct  for  apprehending  and 
expressing  beauty;  a  poet,  able  to  find  earthly  words  for  realities 
unspeakable,  and  for  the  things  of  eternity  a  voice  that  passes  into 

57 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

human  hearts  "with  lightning  and  with  music."  So  that  when  in 
Plato  the  graver  spirit  of  Hellas  entered  into  full  and  critical  pos 
session  of  itself,  and  put  into  words  that  which  it  had  learned  con 
cerning  the  world  and  concerning  life,  the  words  went  forth  to  later 
generations  clad,  in  addition  to  their  scientific  'truth,  with  a  threefold 
power — that  of  humanity,  that  of  beauty,  that  of  religious  passion. 

But  though  Plato's  words  were  at  once  the  profoundest  and  the 
most  human  of  all  the  words  that  have  been  spoken  in  the  schools  of 
philosophy,  the  two  world-ages  which  followed  did  not  take  him  as 
their  teacher.  The  mediaeval  world,  indeed,  might  have  seemed  the 
very  world  for  the  reception  of  Plato.  For  the  men  of  that  world 
were  actually  achieving — to  them  the  supreme  business  of  life  was 
to  achieve — the  very  thing  which  had  lain  closest  of  all  to  Plato's 
heart,  and  which  he  had  called  for  from  the  Greeks  in  vain :  the  sub 
jection  of  the  sensuous  world  to  the  super  sensuous,  the  making  of  the 
wh6le  order  of  the  state,  the  whole  course  of  individual  education, 
the  whole  structure  and  organisation  of  society,  a  "  service  of  the 
invisible  world."1  But,  for  one  thing,  of  the  corpus  of  the  Platonic 
writings  little  beyond  the  Timaeus  was  known.  For  another  thing, 
the  dominant  party  made  religion  inseparable  from  the  church,  and 
the  men  who  laboured  in  the  task  of  giving  to  the  world  its  divine 
interpretation  were  churchmen.  And  these,  when  they  required  an 
intellectual  organon  for  their  immense  endeavour,  found  in  Aristotle 
a  system  remarkably  well  adapted  to  their  needs.  If  it  had  somehow 
been  possible  for  them  to  gain  a  comprehension  of  Plato  as  he  truly 
is,  they  would  probably  have  found  him  a  very  troublesome  friend. 
For  a  spiritual  power,  incalculable,  unfathomable,  not  to  be  fettered 
or  led,  is  a  thing  which  does  not  commend  itself  to  the  typical  church 
man.  And  that  is  precisely  what  Plato  is.  For,  in  the  first  place, 
he  is  always  a  dialectician;  and  his  dialectic  allows  your  mind  no 
rest  except  in  ultimate  and  essential  eternity.  And  in  the  second 
place,  as  we  shall  see  later,2  although  he  is  not  a  Mystic,  yet  Mysticism 
can  be  learned  from  him;  and  Mysticism  makes  short  work  of 
external  organisation,  of  material  symbols,  of  churchly  observances. 

i  Windelband,  Platon,  3te.  Auflage,  S.  169. 
2  Infra,  pp.  214-232. 

58 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

At  the  same  time,  there  is  in  mediaeval  thought  much  more  Platonism 
than  we  usually  fancy;  partly  because  the  mediaeval  temper  led  inde 
pendently  to  it;  partly  because,  in  choosing  Aristotle  as  their  master, 
the  mediaeval  theologians  chose,  next  to  Plato  himself,  the  best  Pla- 
tonist  in  the  world.  And  if  Aristotle  did  not  reach  the  height  of  the 
Platonic  temper,  his  mediaeval  pupils  could  contribute  that  directly 
from  their  own  hearts. 

With  the  modern  world  the  case  has  been  different.  It  could 
know  Plato  if  it  would ;  and  from  the  Eenaissance  onward  it  has  had 
many  ardent  disciples  of  Plato.  But  its  temper  has  in  the  main 
been  un-Platonic;  and  in  its  science  it  began  by  breaking  radically 
with  the  past.  The  world  of  Descartes  and  Bacon,  in  the  extremity 
of  its  revolt  against  the  mediaeval,  would  have  nothing  to  do  with 
any  science  but  its  own;  would  begin  all  over  again  the  work  of 
understanding  the  nature  of  the  world;  would  fight  its  scientific 
battles  altogether  from  its  own  beginning,  altogether  in  its  own 
fashion.  The  outcome  was  remarkable.  When  one  penetrates  to 
the  great  currents  that  beneath  the  troubled  surface  have  driven  for 
ward  as  steadily  and  as  irresistibly  as  if  Necessity  herself  were  in 
them,1  what  one  finds  is  an  almost  exact  parallelism  with  the  course 
of  Greek  thought.  The  Eleatic  and  the  Sophist  are  accurately  in 
their  places  ;  the  Eleatic  (in  Spinoza)  with  much  of  the  old  Par- 
menidean  dignity;  the  Sophist  with  almost  the  old  procedure  in  his 
scepticism.  And  at  last  the  specifically  modern  way  of  approaching 
and  stating  the  problem  was  set  by  a  very  un-Hellenic  Socrates — 
Immanuel  Kant.2  His  work  was  that  of  a  pioneer.  It  furnished 

1  As  a  matter  of  fact,  necessity  was  in  them  ;  the  logical  necessity  which  governs  the/ 
dialectic  evolution  of  the  categories. 

2  Whether  as  a  mere  fact  of  history,  or  an  instance  of  how  the  inner  wisdom  of  history, 
working  under  the  form  of  dialectic  development,  enlists  the  individual  in  its  service, 
this  parallelism  between  the  course  of  Greek  thought  and  that  of  modern,  is  very  striking. 
Both  began   at   the   beginning ;   or  rather,  Thales   actually   did,  and   Descartes   tried- 
Both  settled  with  stubborn  resoluteness  to  the  attempt  to  understand  the  world  from  the 
point  of  view  of  the  category  of  substance.     With  the  Greeks  this  culminated  in  Par. 
menides,  with  the  moderns  in  Spinoza.    Finally  in  each  case  the  lesson  was  learned  (being 
soundly  emphasised  by  the  rise  of  scepticism— Gorgias  and  Protagoras  and  Hume)  that  an 
ontology  cannot  be  constructed  off-hand  ;  that  a  trustworthy  theory  of  reality  can  be 
gained  only  through,  and  in,  and  as,  a  theory  of  knowledge.    The  learning  of  this  lesson  is 
connected  in  the  one  case  with  the  name  of  Socrates,  in  the  other  with  that  of  Kant. 
And  in  each  case  the  learning  of  this  lesson  meant  that  philosophy  entered  auf  den 
sichern  Gang  der  Wissenschaft.    With  the  Greeks  Plato  and  Aristotle  followed ;  with  us, 
the  present  period,  in  which  every  metaphysician  who  is  in  the  main  course  of  philosophy 
and  not  in  some  eddy  or  side-stream,  proceeds  from  the  point  of  departure  set  by  Kant. 

59 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

little  more  than  a  beginning.  And  in  Kant's  own  writings  even  that 
beginning  was  sadly  obscured.  It  was  loaded  down  with  masses  of 
alien  material  and  with  needless  dualisms;  and  it  suffered  especially 

>  because  Kant  dropped  his  own  fundamental  insight  half-way,  and  so 
drew  from  it  almost  the  opposite  of  its  legitimate  conclusions. 
Indeed,  something  like  this  was  to  be  expected;  for  that  insight  was 
the  gain  of  Kant's  old  age,  the  long-delayed  reward  of  a  lifetime  in 
which  that  acute  and  penetrating  intellect  worked  through  the  dog 
matic  and  empirical  and  sceptical  and  sentimental  philosophies  of 
the  day  and  found  rest  in  none  of  them.  But,  under  whatever  weight 
of  alien  and  obscuring  matter,  the  beginning  was  there.  And  the 
task  set  for  the  modern  mind  by  it  has  been  accepted  and  pushed 
resolutely  through.  The  carrying  of  the  Kantian  beginning — if  you 
will,  of  the  Kantian  suggestion — forward  to  its  legitimate  conclusion 

.>has  been  the  special  task  of  metaphysic  in  the  period  of  philosophy 
in  which  we  now  live. 

In  Germany  this  was  done  by  a  succession  of  men  of  thought,  the 

/  last  and  greatest  of  whom  was  Hegel.  Of  him  it  is  sufficient  to  say 
that  each  of  the  great  intellectual  ages  has  given  to  the  world  an 
encyclopaedic  philosopher — a  man  who,  so  far  as  was  possible  to  the 
human  mind,  gathered  into  himself  all  the  science  of  his  day,  and 
interpreted  it  from  the  point  of  view  of  an  insight  into  the  ultimate 
nature  of  reality,  and  so  made  it  in  the  true  sense  of  the  word  a 
system:  the  Greek  age  gave  Aristotle;  the  mediaeval,  Aquinas;  the 
modern,  Hegel. 

But  though  Hegel's  is  the  one  name  that  ranks  with  Aristotle's 
and  with  that  of  Aquinas;  and  though  he  has  written  very  deeply 
upon  many  of  the  more  capacious  minds  of  the  day  his  own  great 
conviction  that  God  actually  is  at  work  in  His  world,  and  that  the 
divine  reasonableness  actually  is  present  in  the  structure  of  the  uni 
verse,  in  the  laws  of  nature,  in  the  course  of  history;  yet  he  is  likely 
never  to  become  a  great  and  familiar  teacher  of  the  human  race,  such 
as  Aristotle  and  Aquinas  have  been  and  are  and  will  be.  In  par 
ticular — and  this  is  what  specially  concerns  ourselves — he  will  never 
in  any  direct  sense  be  the  great  teacher  of  what  for  want  of  some  better 
name  we  must  call  Anglo-Saxondom.  For  one  thing,  his  writings 

60 


AND  THE  VISION  OF   GOD. 

are  often  needlessly  obscure  and  difficult;  and  the  unhappy  form  in<. 
which  it  was  necessary  for  his  editors  to  issue  a  great  part  of  them 
has  not  helped  the  matter.  For  another  thing,  there  is  a  feature  of 
his  work  which  is  peculiarly  distasteful  to  the  "Anglo-Saxon" — or 
at  any  rate  to  the  specifically  English — intellect :  the  technical  appar 
atus,  useful  as  it  really  is,  is  so  enormous  that  sometimes  it  smothers 
the  very  content  for  whose  expression  it  was  devised;  while  at  other 
times  it  carries  Hegel,  rather  than  Hegel  it — at  which  times  the  man 
of  thought  appears  to  be  mounted  upon  a  very  high  horse  indeed.1 

t  At  the  same  time  many  of  us  would  bring  to  our  work  in  the  world  a  graver  and 
more  comprehensive  wisdom  if  we  could  avoid  one  mistake :  we  let  Hegel's  high  words, 
his  masterful  and  comprehensive  procedure,  drive  us  into  rebellion  against  him  and  all 
that  he  represents ;  and  so  we  are  blinded  to  the  fact  that  there  are  things  which  we  need 
to  learn  and  which  his  Idealism  has  to  teach. 

An  example  will  show  what  is  meant.  Lotze  and  Paulsen,  the  one  in  an  earlier  and 
more  irreconcilable  way,  the  other  in  a  later  and  more  moderate,  fought  the  battle  of  the 
steady  everyday  consciousness  against  the  thoroughgoing  procedure  and  vast  results  of 
the  "speculative  philosophy."  But  in  doing  this  they  lost  sight  of  the  fact  that  the  very 
thing  needed  in  order  to  give  coherence  to  their  own  philosophical  construction  is  the 
Kantian  epistemology  as  clarified  and  systematised  by  Hegel.  In  them  philosophy  was 
unnecessarily  crippled ;  not  altogether,  but  to  some  extent,  philosophy  in  them  defeats 
itself;  in  the  name  of  the  ordinary  consciousness  and  of  everyday  interests,  of  the  "solid 
ground  "  and  of  "plain  facts,"  they  recoil  from  precisely  those  scientific  insights  which 
show  us  what  those  everyday  interests  and  ordinary  facts  really  are— the  body,  namely,  of 
an  eternal  reason,  the  media  through  which  and  in  which  an  eternal  purpose  is  being 
realised. 

But  men  such  as  these  bring  to  their  criticism  of  the  "  speculative  philosophy  "  a  fine 
and  high  temper.  "  Sit  anima  mea  cum  illo"  one  has  to  say  of  such  a  man  even  while 
arguing  against  him.  But  one  occasionally  meets  a  very  different  type  of  critic  :  the  man 
who  makes  it  part  of  his  duty  to  pass  in  review  the  "  masters  of  them  that  know  "  simply 
to  find  a  flaw  in  each  and  then  throw  them  all  aside  and  return  triumphantly  within  the 
circle  of  his  own  sectarian — or  individual — theology.  To  such  a  man  Hegel  is  usually 
the  most  special  of  all  his  bugbears.  But  with  such  an  attitude  the  student  who  in 
dealing  with  the  world  of  thought  seeks  its  greater  wisdom  and  its  greater  virtues — and 
only  he  who  is  such  a  student  to-day  is  worthy  to  be  a  leader  of  the  intellect  of  the  church 
to-morrow— will  have  nothing  to  do.  Reverently  he  will  approach  the  world's  masters  in 
science  and  philosophy  ;  he  will  keep  himself  from  the  ingratitude  that  in  the  presence  of 
the  great  workmen  of  the  intellect  seeks  only  to  discover  the  imperfections  of  their  work  ; 
he  will  endeavour  to  make  his  way  through  transient,  and  often  inappropriate,  forms  of 
expression.to  the  inner  and  abiding  meanings,  and  to  do  justice  to  the  truths  that  great 
men  of  old  reached  out  after  but  were  not  able  to  grasp  clearly  and  express  happily;  and 
so  from  each  one — still  more  from  all  of  them  viewed  as  forming  one  great  history  and 
one  great  development— he  will  carry  away  for  himself  a  worthy  harvest  of  insight 
worthily  gained. 

The  fabt  that  in  Germany  itself  there  is  no  "  Hegelian  school  "  is  often  referred  to,  and 
various  inferences  adverse  to  "  Hegelianism  "  drawn  from  it.  But  in  the  first  place  the 
Hegelian  view  of  the  world  is  not  dead ;  it  has  become  part  of  that  intellectual  air  which 
we  all  are  breathing,  and  which  without  Hegel  would  have  been  a  very  different  and  a 
much  poorer  thing.  And  in  the  second  place,  one  of  the  facts  of  German  life  should  be 

61 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

Hence  the  most  trustworthy  of  the  men  of  thought  who  in  Eng 
lish-speaking  countries  have  bent  to  the  work  of  carrying  Kant's 
beginning  forward  to  its  conclusion,  while  they  have  learned  much 
from  Hegel  and  directly  or  indirectly  are  under  profound  debt  to 
him,  are  not  "  Hegelians  " ;  are  not  followers  of  Hegel  in  the  strict 
sense  of  discipleship.1  From  the  point  of  departure  which  Kant  set 
for  us  all,  they  have  gone  forward  with  the  sober  caution  of  their 
race,  and  have  steadily  avoided  any  such  immense  technical  apparatus 

remembered.  In  Germany  the  "  great  masters  "—those  upon  whom  the  young  men  form 
their  minds— are  usually  living  men  ;  you  migrate  from  university  to  university,  look 
upon  their  faces,  hear  them  read.  The  advantages  of  this  are  instantly  apparent.  But  it 
does  not  seem  to  be  equally  well  understood  that  such  a  state  of  affairs  has  at  least  some 
disadvantages.  These  were  never  better  summed  up  than  once  by  the  young  man  who 
later  became  Dr.  Pusey  :  "  There  is  probably  no  people  among  whom  the  mighty  dead  are 
so  soon  forgotten,  or  the  great  names  of  the  present  day  so  unduly  exalted,  as  in  Germany, 
and  this  because  the  knowledge  of  the  mass  of  each  generation  is  derived  for  the  most 
part  exclusively  from  living  sources."  (See  Liddon's  Life  of  Pusey,  1893,  Vol.  I.,  p.  230.) 

For  young  students  it  may  not  be  a  mistake  to  enter  into  Hegel's  system  by  working 
backwards ;  that  is  to  say,  by  beginning  with  the  Philosophy  of  History  (which  as 
Jowett  remarked  to  Tennyson  "is  just  'the  increasing  purpose  that  through  the  ages 
runs'  buried  under  a  heap  of  categories  ")  and  the  Philosophy  of  Right.  Then,— and  all 
the  better  if  with  the  help  of  Mr.  Baillie's,  and  Mr.  M'Taggart's,  valuable  exposition 
and  discussion— the  Logic  can  be  attempted.  Of  introductory  statements  of  Hegel's 
thought  and  of  its  significance,  the  best  remains,  and  is  likely  long  to  remain,  that  by  the 
Master  of  Balliol.  The  handbook  by  Professor  Mackintosh  couples  with  attractive  points 
one  grave  defect.  It  is  described  in  the  preface  as  a  handbook  and  evidently  was  intended 
to  be  such.  But  in  a  handbook  one  thing  is  essential :  it  must  be  an  exposition,  an  expla 
nation,  an  interpretation,  in  the  simplest  and  directest  form  possible,  of  the  system  in 
hand.  To  that  one  purpose  all  the  writer's  literary  powers  and  virtues  should  be  subordi 
nate  and  contributory.  But  Professor  Mackintosh's  discussion,  while  having  any  number 
of  incidental  virtues— it  is  most  interesting  and  suggestive,  full  of  bright  sayings  and 
happy  passages— lacks  precisely  this  essential  quality  of  a  handbook.  One  might  almost 
say  that  so  far  from  being  primarily  an  exposition  of  Hegel  and  of  the  Hegelian  view  of 
the  world,  it  is  an  exposition  of  its  author's  own  opinions,  and  a  somewhat  unfair  criticism 
of  Hegel  in  the  light  of  them.  And  the  treatment  is  very  unequal.  At  some  points 
(whether  in  dealing  with  Hegel  or  with  the  British  teachers  called,  not  quite  fairly, 
"  Hegelians  ")  the  author  writes  like  a  son  of  the  house  describing  to  the  public  the  objects 
of  a  long  and  intimate  knowledge ;  at  others,  with  a  strange  hardness  and  externality, 
almost  (if  the  comparison  may  be  pardoned)  like  a  stranger  who  stands  outside  and  throws 
stones  at  the  windows. 

i  With  regard  to  this,  Professor  Mackintosh,  in  the  handbook  referred  to  in  the 
preceding  note,  does  not  act  quite  as  fairly  as  in  this  age,  when  party  names  mean  so 
unjustly  much,  is  desirable.  To  call  men  "Hegelians"  who  are  Hegelians  only  in  the 
same  sense  that  they  are  Platonists  and  Aristotelians,  is  not  an  example  of  Professor 
Mackintosh's  rule  (op.  cit.  p.  86)  that  "  a  well-chosen  class  name  is  the  first  step  to  knowl 
edge."  The  story  of  Hegel's  influence  upon  British  thought  might  have  been  written 
without  the  application  of  a  party  name  to  men  who  lived  above  party.  And  the  unfair 
ness  is  all  the  graver  that  the  name  is  applied  in  the  face  of  protests  from  the  men 
themselves  who  are  chiefly  concerned. 

62 


AND    THE    VISION    OP    GOD 

as  that  of  Hegel.  This  has  involved,  it  is  true,  the  loss  of  much  that  •• 
was  possible  to  him;  the  great  sweep  of  his  system,  his  vast  and 
orderly  outlook  upon  history,  upon  nature,  upon  all  the  departments 
of  man's  life  and  society.  But  there  has  been  a  corresponding  gain; 
and  that  no  mean  one;  for  the  fundamental  problems,  at  any  rate, 
have  been  treated;  and  treated  with  a  simplicity,  an  intellectual 
severity  and  self-control,  which  put  the  discussion  within  reach  of 
many  to  whom  Hegel  himself  is  ein  'Buck  mil  sieben  Siegeln. 

Among  these  men  there  are  several  toward  whom  the  present 
writer  cherishes  an  affectionate  gratitude  which  grows  deeper  with 
every  year  that  separates  him  from  the  days  when  he  sat  at  their 
feet.  But  it  is  upon  the  name  of  a  man  whose  face  he  has  never 
seen  that  he  desires  at  this  point  specially  to  dwell.  The  late  Pro- 
fessor  Green  had  not  the  special  gifts  of  the  men  to  whom  reference 
has  just  been  made:  not  the  remarkable  blending  of  profundity  and 
subtle  keenness  which  characterises  one  of  them;  not  that  union  of 
philosophic  insight  with  the  whole  breadth  of  humane  learning  which 
gives  charm  to  all  the  work  of  another;  not  the  vast  and  systematic 
range  of  thought  which  makes  a  third  the  representative  of  philosophy 
in  its  true  greatness  as  a  rationally  articulated  view  of  the  world  and 
of  life.  These  things  Green  had  not;  for  his  life  was  weighted  with 
labour  and  his  day  was  short.  But  his  life  and  his  teaching  had  two 
features  which  make  the  mention  of  his  name  specially  appropriate 
in  the  present  connexion.  In  the  first  place,  he  cannot  fairly  be 
called  the  prophet  of  any  "  school."  It  is  true,  he  approached  the 
question  of  the  meaning  of  life  from  the  point  which  Kant  has  made 
inevitable  for  modern  thought.  But  in  the  investigation  itself,  the 
considerations  which  he  brings  forward  and  the  arguments  which  he 
employs  are  elementary,  are  primary  and  simple;  and  just  for  that 
reason  are  fundamental,  and  hold  for  all  life  under  all  circumstances. 
So  that  while  in  one  sense  the  discussion  is  Kantian,  yet  in  a  still 
deeper  sense  to  apply  party  names — Kantian,  Neo-Kantian, 
Hegelian — to  it,  is  as  impossible  as  to  apply  party  names  to  the  first 
and  elementary  principles  of  any  great  science.  And  in  the  second 
place,  while  Green  was,  in  life  and  character,  English  of  the  English, 
and  by  that  character  and  life  spoke  with  Englishmen  heart  to  heart, 

63 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

yet  there  was  operative  in  him  precisely  the  most  valuable  tendency 
of  the  Greek  mind — its  tendency  toward  unity  and  integrity  of  life. 
The  fragments  of  writing  that  he  left  behind  him  give,  if  read  intelli 
gently,  a  systematic  outlook  upon  life — they  contain  both  a  system  of 
fundamental  principles  and  an  application  of  these  to  the  under 
standing  of  nature  and  of  history.  But  that  is  the  lesser  side  of 
the  matter;  if  he  did  not,  in  any  finished  or  technical  sense,  write 
a  system  of  philosophy,  he  lived  one.  What  his  biographer  has  to 
record  is,  as  Mr.  Nettleship  so  well  says,1  "  a  fact  which  has  never 
been  common  and  which  is  especially  rare  in  England,  the  fact  of  a 
life  in  which  philosophy  was  reconciled  with  religion  on  the  one  side 
and  politics  on  the  other ;  the  life  of  a  man  to  whom  reason  was  faith 
made  articulate,  and  for  whom  both  faith  and  reason  found  their 
highest  expression  in  good  citizenship."  It  is  in  men  such  as  this 
that  philosophy  is  most  clearly  seen  doing  the  work  that  it  ought  to 
do  in  every  age,  but  specially  in  an  age  like  our  own;  for  in  such  men 
philosophy  becomes  the  philosophic  mind,  and  the  philosophic  mind 
leads  to  a  life  and  a  work  in  which  the  contending  elements  and 
warring  truths  of  the  age  are  seen  reconciled  and  working  with 
united  power. 

V. 

The  great  argument  which  thus,  from  its  clear  beginnings  in 
Hellas,  passed  onward  through  the  ages  with  all  those  turns  and 
retreats,  and  yet  with  that  very  real  continuity  of  development,  cannot 
be  presented  in  a  few  pages.  Its  full  meaning  can  be  gathered  only 
by  living  through,  in  one's  own  soul,  the  long  course  of  the  history 
in  which  it  struggled  into  possession  of  its  many  insights.  But  a 
sense  of  its  import  can  be  conveyed,  and  an  indication  of  its  procedure 
and  conclusions  given,  by  a  brief  outline  of  its  modern  form — the 
form  which  it  has  taken  in  the  school  of  Kant,  but  which  nevertheless 
is  so  simple  and  elementary  as  to  stand  above  party  affiliations.  In 
attempting  to  draw  up  such  a  statement,  one  of  Green's  writings  is 
specially  useful ;  the  ensuing  outline  was  suggested  by,  and  in  places 

i  In  the  Memoir  prefixed  to  Vol.  III.  of  the  Collected  Works,  p.  xi. 
64 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

follows  quite  closely,  the  argument  worked  out  with  great  simplicity 
but  also  with  great  thoroughness  in  the  Prolegomena  to  Ethics. 

We  must  begin  with  something  which,  as  already  has  been  noticed,1 
was  to  the  greater  masters  of  philosophy  at  once  a  first  insight  and 
an  impulse  to  farther  insight.  In  order  that  our  experience  of  every 
day  things  may  be  what  it  actually  is,  reality  must  be  greater  than  in 
our  everyday  experience  it  seems  to  be.2  Or,  to  put  this  into  the 
narrower  and  more  modern  form  which  exactly  meets  the  problem 
now  before  us,  the  natural  and  physical  sciences,  by  the  very  fact  of 
their  existence,  imply  and  call  for  a  whole  of  knowledge  wider  than 
themselves.  For  all  science  is  a  tracing  out  of  the  relations  of  the 
facts  and  events  of  the  world  to  one  another.  The  laws  of  nature 
which  men  of  science  formulate  are  statements  of  those  abiding  rela 
tions  ;  and  the  total  system  of  such  relations  is  the  order  of  the  world. 
But  suppose  the  natural  and  physical  sciences  to  have  fully  accom 
plished  their  work.  There  would  still  remain  a  relation  to  be  investi 
gated — the  relation  of  all  those  facts  and  events  to  the  knowing 
intelligence.  Every  thing,  every  event,  every  relation,  which  a  man 
of  science  investigates,  enters  by  the  very  fact  of  being  known  and 
investigated  into  a  relation  with  intelligence — into  that  organic  union 
with  intelligence  which  from  the  side  of  the  intelligence  itself  is 
called  knowledge  or  science.  To  say  that  such  a  thing  as  natural 
and  physical  science  exists,  is  to  say  that  mind  and  the  world,  subject 
and  object,  have  entered  into  organic  connexion;  the  knowing  intel 
ligence  has  gone  out  into  the  world,  has  traversed  it,  penetrated  it, 
made  itself  at  home  in  it — and  in  doing  so  has  realised  and  fulfilled 
its  own  nature  as  intelligence ;  or  putting  it  in  another  way,  has  taken 
the  world,  or  parts  and  beginnings  of  the  world,  into  itself,  and  that 
not  as  a  mere  outside  article  drawn  into  an  empty  container,  but  as 
an  organic  part  of  its  own  structure.  This  relation  everything  in  the 
world  that  is  or  ever  can  be  an  object  of  scientific  investigation,  sus 
tains  or  is  capable  of  sustaining;  and  to  say  this,  is  to  say  that  science 
must  advance  to  the  investigation  of  the  relation  in  question.  For 

1  Supra,  pp.  54,  55. 

2  I  have  tried  to  work  this  out  more  fully  in  the  paper  on  Plato,  infra,  pp.  203-247 
(especially  pp.  208-214). 

6  65 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

if  science  be  the  tracing  out  of  the  relations  which  the  constituent 
parts  or  factors  of  the  world  bear  to  one  another,  then  it  is  the  flattest 
of  treasons  against  the  scientific  spirit  to  say,  "We  will  investigate 
certain  classes  of  the  relations  which  make  up  the  world's  order;  but 
with  the  relations  that  fall  outside  those  classes  we  will  have  nothing 
to  do."  The  existence  of  science  is  the  existence  of  this  relation — 
this  relation  of  things  to  intelligence,  of  object  to  subject — and  the 
capacity  for  this  relation  is  part  of  the  nature  of  things.  And  a 
relation  which  thus  exists  and  is  of  the  nature  of  things  must  be 
investigated.  To  refuse  to  investigate  it  would  be  a  turning  of 
science  aside  from  its  regular  and  legitimate  path  of  advance  in 
knowing  the  world ;  would  be  as  genuinely  a  crime  against  the  spirit 
of  science  as  to  refuse  to  investigate  the  laws  of  the  tides,  or  of  the 
planetary  orbits,  or  of  the  development  of  organic  types. 

The  relation,  then,  involved  in  that  organic  connexion  of  objects 
and  intelligence  which  is  science,  must  be  investigated.  And  the 
question  with  which  to  begin  the  investigation  is  a  very  simple  one: 
How  is  such  a  relation  possible  ? 

First  of  all,  let  us  see  what  as  mere  matter  of  fact  the  relation 
amounts  to.  All  science  and  all  endeavour  after  science  presuppose, 
as  already  has  been  pointed  out,  that  the  world  is  one,  a  single  system 
of  facts  and  relations.  Furthermore,  scientific  statements,  once  they 
are  truly  and  adequately  formulated,  are  timelessly  valid  ;  can  be 
handed  on  from  generation  to  generation,  and  stand  firm  independently 
of  time  and  the  passage  of  time.  This  implies  that  the  ultimate  order 
of  that  cosmos  which  it  is  the  business  of  science  to  know  is  an  eternal 
or  timeless  order,  a  single  system  of  fixed  and  unalterable  relations. 
The  upbuilding  of  science  is  a  process  wherein  man  "  enters  into  "  or 
"makes  himself  at  home  in"  or,  more  accurately  still,  "reproduces 
in  and  as  his  own  thought,"  that  system  of  related  facts  which  we 
call  "  the  world,"  that  system  of  eternal  or  timeless  relations  which 
we  call  "  the  order  of  the  world."  And  in  doing  this,  man  acts  the 
part  of  a  permanent  subject  who  (1)  holds  many  diverse  facts  in 
orderly  relation  in  the  unity  of  a  single  conscious  grasp,  and  (2)  in 
so  doing  distinguishes  himself  from  the  various  facts  which  he  thus 
presents  to  himself — distinguishes  himself  from  those  facts  in  the 

66 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

very  activity  of  at  once  distinguishing  them  from,  one  another  and  yet 
relating  them  all  together  in  the  unity  of  one  scientific  view.  And 
must  so  distinguish  himself  from  them;  for  to  carry  on  such  an 
activity  at  all — to  hold,  in  and  as  one  conscious  experience,  a  vast 
variety  of  facts,  keeping  each  one  in  its  own  distinctness,  and  yet 
relating  them  all  together  with  a  continually  growing  accuracy — the 
subject  must,  in  a  certain  genuine  sense,  be  above  each  and  every  one 
of  the  particular  facts  present  to  him ;  must,  to  use  a  metaphor  which 
is  not  the  truth  but  hints  at  the  truth,  be  both  the  judge  to  whom, 
and  the  court  in  which,  they  are  all  present. 

With  this  the  question  we  began  with  is  seen  to  have  two  sides. 
First,  how  is  such  a  world  possible  ?     Secondly,  how  are  we  to  account 
for  the  subject  who  knows  that  world — the  self-conscious  subject,  able 
(partially,  indeed,  and  discursively,  but  still  with  ever-growing  com-*/ 
pleteness)  to  reproduce  that  order  of  nature  in  his  own  thought? 

First,  then,  how  is  such  a  world  possible?  The  world  that  men 
of  science  investigate  is,  as  every  step  of  their  work  presupposes  and 
implies,  "one  connected  world."  It  is  a  single  system.  But  what 
does  that  mean  ?  It  means  two  things :  in  the  first  place  each  of  the 
facts  or  constituent  parts  of  the  world  is  related  to  every  other — the 
total  system  of  those  relations  being  the  "  order  of  the  world  " ;  in 
the  second  place,  each  fact  or  part  is  maintained  in  the  distinctness 
and  integrity  of  its  own  existence,  no  one  of  them  being  in  the  order 
of  nature  fused  or  confounded  with  any  other.  But  how  can  that 
be?  In  the  first  place,  can  it  be  explained  by  supposing  that  each  of 
the  ultimate  constituent  parts  of  the  world — atom,  monad,  or  what 
ever  it  is — institutes  and  maintains  the  total  system  of  its  relations 
with  every  other  part?  Here,  indeed,  there  is  no  space  to  discuss 
such  a  theory  at  length.  But  it  is  not  necessary.  Let  a  man  get 
clear  to  his  mind  all  that  such  a  theory  means — each  atom  (or  elec 
tron,  or  monad,  or  whatever  the  ultimate  constituent  part  is  supposed 
to  be)  from  eternity  an  independent  and  omniscient  consciousness 
which  at  each  instant  (1)  knows  the  movements  (or  other  activities) 
of  all  the  other  atoms  in  the  universe  and  knows  exactly  what  it  should 
do  to  adjust  itself  to  those  movements,  and  (2)  upon  its  own  initia 
tive  and  in  its  own  power  executes  the  adjustment — let  a  man  get  this 

67 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

clear  to  his  mind  and  he  is  not  likely  to  continue  to  hold  the  theory. 
The  solution  given  by  such  a  theory  has  no  relation  to  the  problem 
which  is  being  solved :  it  seeks  to  solve  the  problem  of  "  the  Many 
and  the  One  "  (or  rather  the  Many  in  the  One)  by  giving  us  a  Many 
without  a  One  at  all.  The  theory  which  brings  to  this  problem  of 
the  "  one  connected  world "  a  solution  that  really  does  solve,  and 
therefore  must  be  accepted,  lies  in  the  other  direction.  We  must 
hold,  that  is  to  say,  that  the  existence  of  such  a  thing  as  a  "  connected 
world  "  implies  a  "  principle  of  union  "  which  does  two  things.  It 
links  all  the  facts  together  into  the  unity  of  one  system.  But  at  the 
same  time  and  by  the  same  activity  it  maintains  each  of  them  in  its 
distinctness,  not  fusing  or  confounding  them  together.  And  to  do 
this  it  must  distinguish  itself  from  each  and  all  of  those  facts  or 
events  or  elements  which  it  thus  both  relates  together  and  keeps  dis 
tinct.  To  it  they  all  are  present:  and  since  it  is  only  through  that 
presence  to  it  that  they  have  their  places  in  the  one  system  and  so  are 
what  they  are,  it  may  be  said  on  the  one  hand  that  their  presence  to 
it  is  their  reality;  and  on  the  other  hand  that  it  is  the  source  and 
home  alike  of  them  and  of  their  relations  to  one  another.1 

But  can  science  find  anything  of  which  it  dare  assert  such  an 
activity?  Are  we  acquainted,  in  the  whole  circle  of  our  experience, 
with  anything  which  can  exercise  such  an  activity  and  so  can  be  such 
a  "principle  of  union"?  The  answer  is  that  we  are.  Intelligence, 
r  self-consciousness,  spirit, — or  whatever  other  name  you  may  wish  to 
apply  to  that  which  the  man  of  science  himself  essentially  is — is  pre 
cisely  such  a  principle  of  union  and  exercises  precisely  such  an 
activity.  To  hold  many  facts,  many  elements,  together  in  the  unity 
of  one  grasp,  to  relate  them  together  and  yet  to  keep  each  in  its  dis 
tinctness — this  is  precisely  what  it  is  the  essential  nature  of  self- 
conscious  spirit  to  do.  But  in  applying  this  principle  to  the  solution 
of  our  problem  we  must  remember  that  in  us  men  self-consciousness 
or  spirit  exercises  its  power  of  synthesis  only  imperfectly.  Our 
knowledge  is  fragmentary;  our  minds  in  their  advance,  though  not 

i  This  problem  of  the  "  one  connected  world  "  is,  in  some  form  or  other,  the  problem  of 
all  metaphysicians— even  of  David  Hume.  But  it  is  interesting  to  note  with  what  special 
clearness,  and  how  early,  it  came  forward  in  Greek  thought,  as  the  problem  of  the  Many 
and  the  One. 

68 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

in  their  essential  function,  discursive.  Our  world  is,  in  one  sense, 
a  world  given  to  us,  and  in  apprehending  it  we  pass  from  fact  to 
fact;  in  mastering  one  part  of  it  we  have  to  leave  other  parts  out  of 
sight.  But  self-conscious  spirit,  as  the  principle  of  union  of  the 
world,  cannot  be  fragmentary  or  discursive.  It  must  be  a  single 
eternal  spirit,  to  which  the  total  system  of  things  is  present  in  one 
eternally  complete  grasp  ;x  and  present,  not  as  given  to  it,  but  as  con 
stituted  by  it — constituted  by  it  in  an  activity  in  which  it  acts  alto 
gether  from  itself. 

So,  then,  the  case  thus  far  stands.  We  came  face  to  face  with  a 
problem :  How  can  such  a  thing  as  a  connected  world  exist  ?  Of  the 
two  roads  along  which  a  solution  can  be  sought  we  found  ourselves 
absolutely  shut  up  to  one — that  which  demands  a  "principle  of 
union."  And  something  which  by  its  very  nature  can  act  as  such  a 
principle  we  found  ourselves  to  be  acquainted  with.  We  have,  then, 
a  problem ;  we  have  a  principle  adequate  to  its  solution ;  and  we  have 
but  one  such  principle.  To  the  straightforward  scientific  intellect,- 
when  it  faces  such  a  -situation,  there  is  but  one  course :  to  accept  the 
principle  and  proceed  with  its  farther  application. 

We  must  say,  then,  that  the  world,  as  a  single  system  of  facts,  is 
the  activity  of  a  single  eternal  spirit,  which  by  one  and  the  same 
activity  maintains  the  facts  in  their  distinctness  and  links  them 
together  in  one  system;  and  which,  to  do  this,  must  distinguish 
itself  from  each  and  all  of  the  facts  which  it  thus  constitutes — being 
thus  the  source  and  home  of  the  whole  order  of  the  world,  or  (to  use 
the  technical  language  of  philosophy),  in  the  sense  already  indicated 
the  subject  of  the  world. 

But,  as  we  saw,  in  order  to  explain  how  science  is  possible  more 
is  necessary  than  an  account  of  how  the  objective  world  is  possible. 
For  science  is  the  coming  together  of  the  soul  and  the  world;  is  the 
organic  union  of  subject  and  object.  The  world,  we  have  been  forced 
to  say,  is  a  system  of  facts  present  to  an  eternal  spirit;  it  is  the 
thought  or  activity  of  an  eternal  spirit.  What  then  can  man  be,  who 
in  his  science  reproduces  as  his  own  thought  that  thinking  of  the 
eternal  spirit?  Here,  again,  there  is  no  space  to  do  justice  to  the 

1  Totum  si mul,  as  mediaeval  men  of  thought  were  wont  to  say. 
69 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

argument.  All  that  is  possible  is  to  sum  up  in  the  briefest  form 
its  conclusion.  The  knowing  subject  cannot  be  accounted  for  by 
reference  to  any  of  those  objects,  of  whose  very  existence  as  objects 
of  scientific  study  its  own  synthetic  activity  is  a  necessary  condition. 
NOT  can  it  be  "  derived  "  from  any  of  the  elements  of  its  own  experi 
ence  (such  as  feelings  or  sensations)  ;  for  of  the  very  existence  of 
these  as  elements  of  a  human  experience,  its  synthetic  activity  is,  once 
more,  a  necessary  condition.  It  can  be  accounted  for  only  upon  the 
view  that  the  eternal  subject  of  the  world  has  reproduced  itself — or 
let  us  rather  say,  Himself1 — in  and  as  the  human  subject;  has  repro 
duced  Himself  in  such  a  way  that,  under  whatever  limitations,2  the 
constitutive  principles  of  our  minds  correspond  to  the  constitutive 

i  With  regard  to  this  verbal  usage,  it  is  perhaps  worth  while  to  say  one  thing :  the 
important  matter  is  not  what  pronoun  a  man  chooses,  but  what  he  really  means.  When  a 
writer  (1)  expresses  the  conclusion  that  the  supreme  principle  of  the  world  is  an  eternal 
spirit— a  single  self-conscious  and  self -determining  spirit,  the  eternal  subject  of  the  world, 
perfect  in  intelligence  and  reason ;  (2)  indicates  that  that  eternal  subject  constitutes  the 
whole  order  of  nature,  and  that,  in  order  to  constitute  any  fact  at  all,  it  must  distinguish 
itself  from  each  and  all  of  the  facts  which  it  constitutes  ;  (3)  makes  clear  that  he  derives 
that  conception,  which  for  him  illuminates  the  world,  from  a  consideration  of  the  nature 
and  essential  activity  of  spirit  as  found  in  man  ;  (4)  points  out  that  that  spirit  is  present 
among  men,  is  active  in  the  whole  of  history,  winning  human  hearts  to  itself,  and  through 
them  leading  the  race  of  men  onward  to  an  ultimate  issue  of  divine  love  and  divine 
righteousness :— at  such  a  writer  both  the  Manichsean  and  the  Materialist,  each  from  his 
own  point  of  view,  may  have  cause  to  feel  enraged  ;  but  the  theologian  who  is  a  Theist 
surely  should  recognise  in  him  a  friend,  and  more  than  a  friend.  It  is  a  great  pity  that 
men  who  really  are  agreed  in  the  principles  that  lie  at  the  basis  both  of  their  thought  and 
of  their  conduct,  should  stand  apart  because  they  do  not  understand  one  another's  speech 
—some  using  a  dogmatic  dialect  which  loves  ancient  usages  of  Schools  and  Councils, 
others  a  tongue  which  has  grown  up  in  the  atmosphere  of  science  and  seeks  above  all  things 
(often  with  too  violent  a  forgetfulness  of  the  past)  for  accuracy.  When  we  are  so  unhappy 
as  to  have  to  work  by  words  rather  than  by  action  and  affection,  we  ought,  for  the  sake 
both  of  one  another  and  of  the  truth,  to  do  two  things :  we  ought  to  set  down  our  concep 
tions  with  clearness,  articulating  them  definitely  into  their  constituent  elements  so  as  to 
bring  to  light  those  subconscious  meanings  which  we  all  hold  and  which  shape  our  con 
clusions  (and  our  lives)  much  more  than  we  think  ;  and  we  ought  to  remember  that  most 
words  have  had  histories — the  word  person,  for  instance,  has  taken  on  technical  and  sharply 
limited  meanings  in  two  great  developments,  that  of  Roman  Law,  and  that  of  the 
theological  doctrine  of  the  Trinity— or  to  take  another  instance,  the  word  substance 
expresses  the  category  which  has  revealed  itself  in  history  as  of  all  categories  the  one 
specially  consecrated  to  Pantheism.  Our  Lord's  was  the  better  way,  when,  in  speaking  of 
the  nature  of  God,  He  used  the 'word  Spirit,  and  in  speaking  of  the  relation  of  God  to 
men,  the  word  Father. 

2  Limitations  whose  character  may  be  suggested  by  pointing  out,  for  instance,  that  we 
live  in  time;  that  an  animal  body  is  organic  to  the  process  of  the  development  of  our 
spirits;  that  the  appointed  conditions  of  that  process  of  development  are  such  that  we 
enter  only  by  hard  labour,  and  by  struggles  and  sorrows  which  go  beyond  all  hardness  of 
labour,  into  our  inheritance  of  knowledge  and  of  character. 

70 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

principles  of  that  thought  or  activity  of  His  which  is  the  world.  For 
that  reason,  and  only  for  that  reason,  are  we  men  able  to  make  our 
selves  at  home  in  the  nature  which  He  constitutes,  whether  when,  as 
children,  we  played  amongst  its  flowers,  or  when  we  investigate  it 
scientifically,  or  when,  in  times  of  happiness  and  still  more  in  times 
of  trouble  and  of  loss,  we  find  in  it  a  companion  and  stay  of  our 
spirits: — just  as  a  reader  is  able  to  study  a  book,  and  gradually  to 
enter  into  its  meaning,  and  gradually  to  have  his  mind  strengthened 
and  uplifted  by  it,  because,  and  only  because,  the  constitutive  prin 
ciples  of  his  mind  and  being  are  in  their  essential  character  the  same 
as  those  of  the  writer  of  the  book. 

Such,  then,  is  the  account  which  must  be  given,  on  the  one  hand 
of  the  world  which  is  known,  on  the  other  hand  of  the  soul  which 
knows.  But  the  two  questions  to  which  these  are  answers  were  the 
two  sides  of  the  one  question:  How  is  knowledge  possible?  And  it 
is  when  we  come  back  to  that  question  in  its  unity,  and  put  our  two 
answers  together  as  the  answer  to  it,  that  we  see  the  deepest  strength 
of  the  whole  argument  and  of  the  conclusion  to  which  it  leads.  Man 
is  able  to  know  nature — to  have  science  of  nature — only  because  there 
is  an  essential  likeness  between  man  and  nature.  The  soul  is  able  to 
go  out  into  the  world  and  make  itself  intellectually  at  home  in  the 
world — is  able  to  take  the  world  into  itself  and  reproduce  in  and  as 
its  own  thought  that  system  of  facts  and  laws  which  is  nature — 
because,  and  only  because,  nature  is  really  what  the  soul  is,  a  spiritual 
existence;  because,  and  only  because,  nature  is  the  thought  of  God 
and  man  is  the  child  of  God,  able,  no  matter  how  imperfectly  and 
gradually,  to  think  his  Father's  thoughts  after  Him.1 

That  insight  has  never  been  better  stated  than  in  words  which 
tradition  ascribes  to  a  man  of  science.  Kepler,  seeing  that  the  power 
which  carried  on  the  stellar  movements  was  acquainted  with,  and 
acted  in  the  most  exact  accordance  with,  those  mathematical  prin 
ciples  which  he  himself  had  worked  out  in  the  council-chamber  of  his 
own  pure  reason,  turned,  it  is  said,  from  his  telescope  with  the 
exclamation,  "  I  think  Thy  thoughts  after  Thee,  0  God/'  Cases  of 

i  This  is  often  expressed  by  saying  that  science  is  spirit  finding  itself  in  nature  ;  and 
that  spirit  can  find  itself  in  nature,  only  because  nature  itself  is  spirit. 

71 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

this  sort,  which  nowadays  occur  ever  more  frequently — cases  in  which 
men  of  science  come  to  conclusions  mathematically  (i.e.,  by  the  way 
of  the  pure  reason),  and  then,  turning  to  the  telescope  or  to  the  labor 
atory,  find  that  these  conclusions  are  true  of  nature — are  very  marked 
instances  of  the  community  of  the  intelligence  which  is  nature  with 
the  intelligence  which  is  man.  But  the  same  view  of  the  world  and 
of  the  soul  which  is  needed  to  explain  the  possibility  of  these,  is 
needed  to  explain  any  knowledge  of  nature  by  man  at  all,  even  though 
it  be  but  the  little  child's  knowledge  of  the  flowers  among  which  it 
plays,  or  the  primitive  shepherd's  rough  acquaintance  with  the  laws  of 
wind  and  weather  or  the  ways  of  plant  and  animal  life. 

What  we  have  seen  so  far  we  may,  then,  sum  up  in  this  way :  ( 1 ) 
The  system  or  process  of  nature  is  a  divine  activity;  is,  if  you  will, 
part  of  the  divine  thought.  (2)  Our  sciences  of  nature  are  the 
thinking  of  the  thoughts  of  One  who  is  invisible — a  thinking  of  God's 
thoughts  after  Him.  The  growth  of  these  sciences  may  be  described, 
from  our  side,  as  our  gradual  entering  into,  or  comprehending  of,  or 
making  ourselves  at  home  in,  the  content  of  the  divine  mind;  and 
from  the  divine  side,  as  God's  gradual  impartation  of  His  thought 
to  us.  (3)  And  this  process  of  thinking  God's  thoughts  after  Him, 
of  reading  the  book  which  He  has  written — the  book  whose  syllables 
are  the  growth  of  the  flowers,  and  the  ordered  march  of  the  stars,  and 
the  age-long  development  of  animal  organisms — is  possible  to  us 
because,  and  only  because,  God  has  reproduced  Himself  in  us; 
because,  and  only  because,  we  are  His  children,  made,  intellectually, 
in  His  likeness,  having  our  essential  cognitive  principles  the  same  as 
the  principles  of  the  divine  intelligence;  because,  and  only  because, 
to  use  an  accurate  but  easily  misunderstood  expression,  the  human 
mind  is  potentially  the  divine  mind. 

So,  then,  even  if  we  stopped,  at  this  point  of  the  metaphysician's 
regress  upon  the  conditions  of  experience,  we  could  affirm  at  least  this 
much : — In  every  step  and  at  every  stage  both  of  the  nature  which  is 
known  and  of  man's  activity  in  knowing  it,  the  presence  and  activity 
of  the  Eternal  is  implied.  The  whole  process  of  the  building  up  of 
the  natural  and  physical  sciences  is  a  co-working  of  man  with  God, 
of  the  human  mind  with  the  divine  mind.  It  is  a  participation  of 

72 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

man  in  the  Eternal  Reason;  is,  for  him  who  is  willing  to  see  the 
meaning  of  his  own  endeavours  after  science,  part  of  the  process 
whereby  God  becomes  our  dwelling-place  and  the  home  of  our  spirits. 
So  that,  even  while  the  movement  of  history  and  the  growth  of  mind 
are  stripping  away  from  cleric  and  priest  and  altar  something  of  their 
awful  splendour  and  long-asserted,  compelling  power,  the  sciences  of 
nature  have  a  sanctity  which  is  immediate  and  cannot  by  any  move 
ment  of  history  or  change  of  institutions  be  shaken.  For  the  courts 
of  science,  whether  the  men  who  labour  in  them  recognise  it  or  no, 
are  sacred  with  the  most  immediate  presence  of  the  ultimate  God. 
And  their  sanctity  is  but  part  of  a  wider  sanctity.  To  him  who  is 
able  to  see  the  meaning  and  significance  of  science,  every  ray  of  light 
that  the  man  of  science  flashes  from  his  mirror,  every  minutest 
animal  cell  that  he  examines  under  his  microscope,  together  with  his 
own  power  of  knowing  these  objects,  is  a  witness  that  the  world  hev 
dwells  in  is  at  once  the  activity  and  the  temple  of  the  Most  High  God. 
Newman  to  some  extent  apprehended  this.  "  Every  breath  of 
air,"  he  somewhere  says,  "  and  ray  of  light  and  heat,  every  beautiful 
prospect,  is,  as  it  were,  the  skirts  of  their  garments,  the  waving  of 
the  robes  of  those  whose  faces  see  God."  But  this  is  rather  the  word 
of  the  preacher  catching  a  momentary  glimpse  of  the  glory  of  his 
God  revealed  in  alien  realms,  than  any  assured  and  thoroughgoing 
vision  of  the  real  being  of  nature.  For,  in  the  first  place,  Newman 
the  churchman  (using  that  word  for  a  moment  as  Newman  himself 
would  have  used  it)  loyal  to  the  very  letter  of  the  dogma  of  his 
church,  could  scarcely  look  otherwise  than  askance  upon  nature,  and 
upon  the  sciences  of  nature,  and  upon  the  independent  endeavour  of 
philosophy  to  penetrate  to  the  ultimate  meaning  both  of  nature  and 
of  man's  knowledge  of  nature.  And  secondly — a  worthier  reason- 
he  felt  so  acutely  the  revelation  of  God  in  conscience  and  in  man's 
inner  heart,1  that  he  tended  to  overlook  the  revelation  of  God  in 
nature,  and  to  have  no  eyes  for  the  fact  that  all  knowledge  of  nature 
is  in  ultimate  analysis  knowledge  of  God,  and  is  possible  to  man  only 
through  and  as  God's  impartation  of  Himself  to  man. 

i  See  his  description  of  his  early  religious  feelings  on  p.  4  of  the  new  edition  of  the 
Apologia:  .  .  .  "making  me  rest  in  the  thought  of  two  and  two  only  absolute  and 
luminously  self-evident  beings,  myself  and  my  Creator,  j 

73 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

But  in  Wordsworth  we  find  both  adequate  vision — I  had  almost 
said,  adequate  comprehension — and  adequate  expression.      The  per 
ception  of  what  nature  truly  is;  and  the  companion  perception  of 
what  the  true  strength  of  our  human  life  is  : — these  are    the  ani 
mating  and  informing  soul  of  his  poetry.1     That  the  contemplation 
of  nature,  the  love  of  nature,  the  companionship  with  nature,  is  a 
companionship  in  which  we  lay  aside  our  mortality,  a  companionship 
in  which  God  imparts  his  mind  to  man  and  man's  mind  comes  to 
dwell  in  its  own  proper  home,  its  home  in  God : — this  is  the  essential 
principle  of  Wordsworth's  vision  of  nature.     It  is  in  this  companion 
ship  with  nature  that  we  become  living  souls  and  see  into  the  life  of 
things,  and  the  burthen  of  the  mystery,  the  heavy  and  the  weary 
weight  of  all  this  unintelligible  world,  is  lightened,  and  we  become 
aware  of  a  deeper  presence  than  before  we  had  known,  something 
far  more  deeply  interfused  than  our  first  rapturous  acquaintance  with 
nature,  our  first  delight  in  her  glory  of  sound  and  colour,  had  taught 
us — 

Something  far  more  deeply  interfused, 
Whose  dwelling  is  the  light  of  setting  suns, 
And  the  round  ocean  and  the  living  air, 
And  the  blue  sky,  and  in  the  mind  of  man  ;  • 
A  motion  and  a  spirit,  that  impels 
All  thinking  things,  all  objects  of  all  thought, 
And  rolls  through  all  things. 

And  it  is  Wordsworth's  special  crown  of  glory  that  with  him  this 
vision  of  the  divinity  of  nature  became  also  a  vision  of  the  sacredness 
of  the  ordinary  life  of  man  with  its  natural  relationships,  its  natural 
duties,  its  natural  charities.  For  him  the  heavenly  light  rested,  as 
upon  the  lakes  and  silent  hills,  so  also  upon  the  elemental  constituents 
of  the  life  of  man.  The  two  together  formed  the  one  object  of  his 
work  as  a  poet.  For  these  as  for  those,  he  sought — not  to  bring  a 
consecration  of  poetic  light  from  without — but  to  penetrate  to,  and 
interpret,  the  heavenly  nature  which  is  their  genuine  being. 

i  Perhaps  one  ought  rather  to  say  that  these  are  the  light  of  his  poetry,  the  truth  and 
insight  which  his  poetry  expresses ;  while  its  warmth,  the  restrained  but  immense  power 
that  is  in  it,  comes  from  his  own  English  heart— a  heart  most  affectionate,  and  trained 
(like  Plato's)  by  long  discipline  of  tragic  passion  and  deep  peace. 

74 


AND    THE    VISION    OF  _  GOD 

Upon  this  it  is  worth  while  to  pause  a  moment  longer.  For  it 
explains  a  fact  most  significant  in  itself  and,  to  men  of  the  church, 
full  of  instruction.  It  may  appear  remarkable  in  the  extreme  that 
men,  for  religions  sake,  should  take  refuge  from  a  prophet  with  a 
poet.  And  yet,  when  Newman  is  the  prophet  and  Wordsworth  the 
poet,  that  is  what,  to  a  certain  extent  and  in  a  certain  regard,  we 
ordinary  men  living  the  ordinary  life  have  to  do.  For  (even  leaving 
aside  the  fact  that  Newman,  with  all  the  intensity  of  his  vision  of  the 
divine,  came  at  last  to  look  upon  a  single  narrowly  defined  institu 
tion  as  the  one  thing  in  this  world  directly  and  distinctly  of  divine 
foundation),  the  very  intensity  of  his  vision  of  the  unity  of  this  life 
with  the  life  to  come  dimmed  his  eyes  to  the  unity  of  man  with 
nature,  and  to  the  value  of  nature  and  of  the  natural  man  to  God. 
But  the  unity  of  man  with  nature,  and  the  unity  of  nature  with  God, 
Wordsworth  saw  with  the  clear  vision  of  a  daily  and  affectionate 
friendship. 

Hence  it  is,  too,  that  while  we  are  still  young  Newman's  lesson  is 
the  easier  to  learn  and  is  the  one  that  specially  wins  us ;  but  when  we 
grow  older  it  is  more  and  more  to  Wordsworth  that  we  turn  both  for 
illumination  and  support.  When  we  are  young,  and  our  hearts  beat 
high,  and  the  burden  of  the  daily  life  has  not  fully  come  upon  us, 
it  is  easy  for  us  to  despise  the  vanities  of  the  world.  It  is  easy  to 
turn  away  from  the  noises  of  the  earth,  and  from  the  littlenesses  of 
the  "  practical  life/'  and  to  enter  upon  that  short  and  direct  road  to 
the  heavenly  glory  which  consists  in  repudiating  the  earth  and'  all 
its  ways.  But  when  we  grow  older,  and  life  itself  puts  us  in  our 
places,  and  we  are  grappling  day  by  day  with  the  tasks  of  the 
ordinary  life,  and  either  in  them  or  not  at  all  must  fulfil  the  vocation 
which  we  have  from  God;  then  we  learn  with  a  continually  deepen 
ing  gratitude  to  receive  Wordsworth's  lesson  of  the  essential  sacred- 
ness  of  the  natural  relationships,  of  the  natural  charities  and  affec 
tions,  of  the  natural  surroundings,  of  our  daily  life.  It  is  not  that  • 
Newman  ever  loses  his  high  spiritual  majesty  in  the  eyes  of  any  man 
who  has  once  apprehended  it;  it  is  that  Wordsworth  comes  nearer  to 
us,  and  dwells  with  us  in  our  daily  cares,  and  illuminates  our  daily 
and  natural  life  with  divine  and  eternal  light,  showing  us  nature 

75 


THE    STUDY    OF   NATURE 

and  natural  affection  as  a  work  of  the  grace  of  God  and  as  a  medium 
for  the  farther  impartation  of  that  grace  to  us. 

But  we  must  return  to  the  argument  itself.  For  the  point 
reached  a  moment  ago  was  one  at  which  we  cannot  stop.  The  insight 
so  far  gained  compels  us  to  take  a  further  step.  And  to  that  step 
we  are  driven  whether  we  view  the  matter  from  the  divine  or  from 
the  human  side. 

First  from  the  divine  side.  We  have  seen  that  the  order  of  the 
world  in  accordance  with  which  the  world's  history  proceeds,  is  con 
stituted  by  an  eternal  spirit  who  is  the  subject  of  the  world;  in  a 
^word,  we  have  seen  that  the  world  is  the  thought  or  activity  of  God. 
But  spirit,  in  any  activity  which  has  the  form  of  time,  proceeds 
teleologically.  It  "sees  the  end  from  the  beginning,"  and  in 
view  of  that  end  it  arranges  the  beginning,  arranges  the  essential 
conditions,  the  informing  order  and  constitution  of  the  whole  process. 
It  is  involved,  then,  in  the  position  already  reached — nay,  it  is  involved 
in  anything  that  can  be  called  Theism — that  that  whole  activity  of  God 
in  which  Tie  constitutes  the  order  of  the  world  and  maintains  the  world, 
proceeds  in  view  of  an  end  or  r*Ao<r. 

Or  if  we  start  from  the  human  side  we  come  to  precisely  the  same 
point  and  almost  by  the  same  road.  For  man's  life,  so  far  at  any  rate 
as  he  enters  into  his  moral  and  intellectual  heritage,  is  a  process  of 
development ;  nature  itself,  which  is  at  once  the  beginning,  the  home, 
and  the  stubborn  material,  of  our  life,  being  a  medium  which  God 
uses  in  what  may  be  described  indifferently  as  the  communication  of 
His  mind  to  us,  or  as  the  development  of  our  own  minds.  And  so 
there  arises  the  question :  In  a  world-order  which  is  rational,  which 
is  constituted  by  an  eternal  and  self-conscious  Reason,  what  can  be 
the  significance  of  such  a  possibility  of  human  development?  what 
can  be  the  meaning  of  the  fact  that  the  form  into  which  our  life  is 
cast  is  the  form  of  development  ?  Here  also  the  position  already 
reached  leaves  us  but  one  possible  answer.  The  eternal  subject  of  the 
world,  who  does  not  act  wantonly  or  blindly  or  irrationally,  who  does 
not  make  experiments,  and  to  whom  it  is  impossible  to  institute  a 
beginning  that  forgets  its  end,  has  constituted  the  world,  with  its 

76 


AOT)    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

possibility  of  human  development,  in  view  of  a  rAos  which  would 
be  a  true  and  genuine  fulfilment  of  the  beings  and  the  capacities  that 
are  the  subjects  of  the  development. 

From  both  sides,  then,  we  are  brought  to  the  conception  of  an  end 
or  Tt\os  in  view  of  which  God  proceeds  in  that  activity  by  which  the^ 
order  of  the  world  is  constituted  and  the  process  of  the  world's  history 
made  possible.  And  the  next  step  of  the  argument  whose  course  and 
whose  conclusions  are  being  noted  here,  is  an  attempt  to  understand 
more  particularly  what  that  rtkos  can  be.  Since  the  order  of  the 
world  in  which  we  now  live  is  constituted  in  view  of  that  rAo?,  cer 
tain  conclusions  concerning  the  latter  are  possible  from  a  considera 
tion  of  the  former.  Two  of  these  may  in  the  briefest  possible  form 
be  indicated  here.  In  the  first  place,  that  "far-off  divine  event" 
consists  in  a  perfect  society,  a  fully  realised  "kingdom  of  God/'  in 
which  the  capabilities  of  men,  moral,  intellectual,  artistic,  developed 
only  in  part — often  scarcely  at  all,  and  sometimes  worse  than  not  at  - 
all — in  this  world,  reach  their  true  and  full  development;  and  in 
which  one  person  does  not  enter  into  his  good  at  the  expense  of 
another ;  but  on  the  contrary  the  good  of  all  is  the  good  which  each  one 
seeks,  and  therefore  the  attainment  of  his  good  by  any  individual  " 
means  to  that  extent  the  attainment  of  the  good  by  all.  In  the 
second  place,  the  perfection  of  personal  character  which  is  implied  in 
the  perfection  of  that  society,  is  not  only  present  to  the  divine  mind 
as  an  idea;  it  exists,  fully  and  eternally  realised,  in  the  divine  char- 
art  or.  In  moral  character,  God  Himself  is,  in  eternal  completeness, 
that  toward  which  it  is  the  vocation  of  the  sons  of  God  to  grow ;  such 
is  the  End  which  is  at  once  the  promise  of  our  life,  and  the  measure 
of  its  genuine  value,  and  the  standard  which  sets  in  a  light  more  awful 
than  that  of  any  day  of  wrath  its  present  distance  from  its  goal.  So 
that  science,  in  the  last  saying  which  it  makes  possible,  places  us 
among  those  multitudes  of  men  who,  with  a  sorrow  upon  which  a 
great  hope  is  dawning,  listen  to  that  other  saying  which  is  at  once  the 
judgment  and  the  inspiration  of  their  lives:  "Ye  shall  be  perfect," 
even  as  your  Father  which  is  in  heaven  is  perfect." 

This  then  is,  from  the  divine  side,  the  rf'Ao?  of  the  world;  from 
the  human  side,  it  is  man's  eternal  vocation.    And  the  way  of  the  ful- 

77 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATIJEE 

filment  of  that  vocation  is  the  way  of  the  cross;  the  way,  as  the 
greatest  of  modern  metaphysicians  so  steadily  insisted,  of  "  dying  in 
order  to  live";  the  way  of  that  self -surrender  in  which  men  yield 
themselves  up  to  be  the  organs  of  the  eternal  purpose,  and  become,  if 
one  may  thus  express  it,  subordinate  centres  of  the  activity  of  the 
divine  will,  realising  their  own  true  freedom  and  coming  genuinely 
"  to  have  life  in  themselves  "  precisely  in  the  measure  that  they  appre 
hend  the  divine  purpose,  and  obey  the  vocation  which  the  very 
existence  of  that  purpose  constitutes  for  man. 

With  this  latter  insight — the  insight  that  men  come  truly  to  be 
themselves,  that  they  realise  their  true  freedom  and  come  genuinely 
to  have  life  in  themselves,  only  as  they  implicitly  or  explicitly  appre 
hend  the  divine  purpose  and  obey  the  vocation  which  the  existence  of 
such  a  purpose  constitutes — the  broad  and  general  argument  whose 
course  we  have  in  this  section  been  following,  comes  full  circle. 
From  a  problem  of  human  life  it  began,  and  now  it  returns  upon 
human  life.  On  the  field  of  human  history — which  in  the  last 
analysis  means  on  the  field  of  man's  daily  life — the  eternal  subject 
of  the  world  is  operating  toward  the  realisation  of  His  purpose;1  but 
not  by  iron  assertion  and  enforcement  of  sovereignty ;  nor  by  mechan 
ical  action  of  the  divine  will  or  the  divine  grace  upon  man,  such  as 
in  the  common  conception  of  things  a  physical  force  exercises  upon 
a  physical  object.  Rather  the  divine  mind  operates  in  human  history 
toward  the  realisation  of  its  purpose,  by  imparting  to  the  human  mind 
ideas  and  strivings  which,  however  imperfect,  are  in  a  certain  genuine 
sense  "representatives  to  man"  of  the  eternal  ideal,  and  which, 
becoming  operative  powers  in  men's  lives,  lead  human  history  on 
toward  its  goal.  The  historical  process  of  the  realisation  of  the  divine 
idea  is  worked  out,  that  is  to  say,  neither  by  mechanical  action  nor  by 
"mere  sovereignty"  on  God's  part,  but  in  and  through  that  which 
when  viewed  from  man's  side,  is  "man's  devotion  to  the  highest 
ideal  that  he  knows,"  and  which  when  viewed  from  God's  side  may 
be  described  as  "  God  reconciling  the  world  to  Himself."2  In  other 

1 1  am  stating  this  from  the  point  of  view  of  philosophy  and  in  the  language  of 
philosophy ;  and  am  so  stating  it  because  it  is  a  conclusion  of  philosophy.  But  it  may  not 
be  amiss  to  refer  to  such  passages  of  Scripture  as  John  v.  17. 

2  Cf.  (under  the  qualification  mentioned  in  the  last  note)  Col.  i.  20 ;  2  Cor.  v.  18,  19. 

78 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

words,  the  divine  idea  realises  itself  in  history  by  an  impartation  of 
itself  in  which  it  wins  men  as  free  spirits  to  its  service.  By  impulses 
planted  in  man's  nature;  by  the  appeal  that  suffering  makes,  and  by 
all  the  efforts  undertaken  to  alleviate  it;  by  natural  affection  and 
all  "the  charities  of  father,  son,  and  brother";  by  the  institutions, 
the  needs,  the  opportunities,  of  society  and  social  life;  by  prophetic 
energies  aroused  in  solitary  and  burning  hearts;  by  the  ideals  that 
under  the  pressure  of  some  great  need  arise  in  men's  minds,  and 
move  upon  the  face  of  a  people's  life,  and  win  to  their  service  its  suc 
cessive  generations;  in  a  word,  in  all  that  can  be  described  as  the 
natural  development  of  morality  and  the  natural  growth  of  society; 
and  in  that  in  which  divine  revelation  culminates — the  character  and 
action  of  Jesus,  wherein  the  ideal  for  human  life,  and  the  constitutive 
principle,  the  eternal  and  ultimate  law,  of  the  whole  order  of  the 
universe,1  stand  revealed  in  absolute  simplicity  for  all  men's  appre 
hension: — in  all  this  the  divine  idea  has  been  at  work,  and  is  at 
work,  winning  to  itself  all  men  that  can  be  won,  and  through  them 
leading  onward  the  course  of  history  and  introducing  into  time  the 
principles  and  the  powers  of  eternity.2 

1  Cf.  Col.  i.  16, 17  (R.V.). 

2  I  may  perhaps  be  allowed  a  single  historical  reference.    The  great  deterministic 
theologies  (one  hesitates  to  use  party  names  like  "  Calvinistic  "  or  "  Augustinian  ")  tended 
to  make  the  divine  purpose  execute  itself  in  almost  the  same  way  as  the  force  which 
drives  a  machine  fulfils  itself  through  the  various  parts  of  the  machine,  none  of  which 
have  "  life  in  themselves  "  or  any  will  of  their  own  or  any  energy  different  from  the  energy 
of  the  one  total  machine  of  which  they  are  parts.    Against  these  deterministic  theologies, 
which  were  really  great  one-sided  philosophies,  Arminianism  was  a  protest,  not  so  much 
of  the  philosophic  intellect  of  man  as  of  his  outraged  moral  nature.    And,  as  such  a 
protest,  it  never  worked  out  adequately  the  great  truth  which  it  had  felt  keenly  rather 
than  apprehended  rationally.    Indeed,  it  has  been  almost  ostentatiously  non-philosophical 
—seeking  for  practice  without  seeking  for  the  reason  of  practice,  and  being  historically 
less  able  to  secure  that  very  practice  than  its  grim  but  convinced  opponent.    But  the 
philosophy  of  the  matter  is  clear.    And  it  is  one  in  which  Calvinist  and  Arminian  may 
very  well  unite.    God  is  certainly  supreme  in  His  world ;  the  divine  plan  certainly  supreme 
in  history.    In  its  resolute  and  unflinching  affirmation  of  that,  Augustinian  and  Calvin 
istic  theology  had  its  hands  upon  a  great  truth ;  and  in  that  fact  lies  the  explanation  of  its 
immense  practical  power  and  efficiency.    But,  understood  truly,  that  divine  plan  prevails, 
not  as  the  sovereignty  of  an  iron  machine  over  its  parts,  but  by  "  reconciling  men  to 
itself  "  ;  by  winning  to  itself  the  hearts  and  wills  of  men  so  that  they  devote  themselves 
to  it  to  be  its  organs,  and  it  has  in  them  the  spontaneous  and  yet  subordinate  centres  of  its 
work  of  realising  itself. 

But  the  men  whose  thoughts  have  lived  with  the  past  struggles  of  the  human  mind  to 
understand  the  ways  of  God,  even  while  under  the  leadership  of  a  modern  metaphysician 

70 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 
VI. 

Such,  then,  is  the  point  of  view  of  that  "  greater  whole  of  knowl 
edge  "  which  the  natural  and  physical  sciences  by  their  very  existence 
imply  and  call  for.  What  is  gained  from  that  point  of  view  is  an 
insight,  not  into  the  complete  detail  of  the  system  of  the  world,  but 
into  its  essential  and  ultimate  nature :  in  that  sense  it  is  a  "  knowledge 
of  the  world  as  a  whole/'  And  such  a  knowledge  of  the  world  as  a 
whole  is  an  interpretation  of  the  meaning  of  life;  for  it  is  an  account 
of  the  true  character  of  that  order  of  the  world  by  which  the  condi 
tions  of  our  life  are  set.  Whether  this  knowledge  be  called  theology 
(as  finding  the  truth  of  the  world  in  God),  or  philosophy  of  nature, 
or  philosophy  of  mind,  matters  little.  For  man  is  the  son  of  God; 
and  nature  is  that  thought  of  God  which  is  God's  medium  in  com 
municating  His  mind  to  man,  and  thus  developing  in  man  man's  own 
mind.  So  that  to  know  nature,  God  and  man  must  be  known ;  and  to 
know  man,  God  and  nature  must  be  known.  Any  one  of  the  three — 
theology;  philosophy  of  mind;  philosophy  of  nature — in  order  to  be 
itself  must  be  the  other  two;  and  to  the  extent  that  it  is  not,  it 

they  point  out  that  those  antithetic  views  can  be  unified  in  a  more  comprehensive  truth, 
know  that  the  schools  of  theology  themselves  have  something  better  to  show  than  one 
sided  systems.  Among  those  who  have  inquired  concerning  the  relation  of  the  world's 
history— the  relation  of  the  wills,  the  characters,  the  fates,  of  individuals  and  societies— 
to  the  divine  nature,  there  is  a  greater  than  either  Augustine  or  the  Remonstrant  against 
Augustine.  If  we  are  to  be  disciples  in  the  schools  of  theology  at  all,  the  minds  that  are 
deepest  and  the  hearts  that  most  love  God  and  live  most  in  that  love,  will  go  back,  it 
seems  to  me,  past  both  these  men  of  the  West  to  that  great  and  undying  light  which  was 
the  soul  of  Origen.  If  the  word  theology  be  taken  in  its  strict  sense  as  the  human 
scientific  wisdom  which  seeks  to  know  God  and  to  interpret  the  facts  of  the  world  in  the 
light  of  that  knowledge,  Origen  is  the  greatest  of  theologians.  Greatest  because  he  saw 
two  things :  that  the  conception  of  the  divine  nature  is  the  supreme  principle  in  theology  ; 
and  that  the  divine  nature  is  love.  He  was  not  subject  to  that  habit  to  which  the  Western 
mind  continually  (and  very  naturally)  gave  way;  the  habit  of  confining  God's  love,  and 
all  the  communicative  and  disciplinary  energies  of  that  love,  within  th.e  barriers  of 
artificial  legal  requirement.  To  apprehend  the  meaning  for  theology  of  the  love  of  God, 
one  must  one's  self  live  in  that  love ;  and  live  in  it  with  width  of  heart  and  spaciousness 
of  mind.  And  to  say  that  is  precisely  to  describe  Origen.  In  contrast  with  the  spirit  of 
Origen,  the  tragedy  of  Western  theology  lies  in  the  fact  that  it  has  been  too  much  the 
work  of  the  political  and  legal  (indeed  of  the  positively  lawyer-like)  mind,  which  in 
theology  tends  to  view  the  rectifying  of  the  relation  of  the  sinful  human  race  to  God  as  a 
matter  of  mere  transactions ;  transactions  carried  through  by  steps  which  are  not  ethical 
realities  but  rather  are  forensic  conventions,  external,  artificial,  unreal.  Not  that  the 
West  has  been  without  hearts  that  have  lived  in  the  love  of  God.  That  which  is  deepest 
and  most  vital  in  the  life  of  the  West  has  been  brought  into  being  precisely  by  such 

80 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

ceases  to  have  the  form  of  science  and  becomes  the  voice  of  authority. 
For  the  world  is  one;  the  ultimate  order  of  the  world  is  one;  the 
knowledge  of  that  ultimate  order  is  one;  and  that  one  knowledge  is 
at  once  theology  and  philosophy  of  mind  and  philosophy  of  nature. 
With  the  emphasis  at  one  point,  it  is  theology  (in  the  sense  noted  a 
moment  ago) ;  with  the  emphasis  at  another  point,  it  is  philosophy 
of  mind  (which,  in  the  only  useful  or  respectable  sense  of  the  term, 
means  philosophy  of  history  and  of  society,  with  all  that  history  and 
society  include  of  moral  and  intellectual  endeavour)  ;  with  the 
emphasis  at  still  another  point,  it  is  philosophy  of  nature. 

And  this  knowledge,  by  whatever  name  it  is  called,  is  made  pos 
sible  to  us  by  the  fact  that  the  "  masters  of  them  that  know,"  in  their 
long  endeavour  to  understand  nature,  have  steadily  refused  to  stop 
half-way  in  the  knowledge  of  nature;  have  refused  to  be  contented 
with  a  study  of  the  detailed  facts  of  nature  as  mere  facts ;  have  stub 
bornly  endeavoured  to  penetrate  to  the  true  character  of  nature  as 
an  order  or  system ;  and  have  found  that  the  scientific  gateway  to  this  v 
knowledge  is  the  gateway  of  epistemology.  For  to  the  insight  into 
the  ultimate  character  of  nature  they  made  their  way  by  considering 
the  fact  that  nature  is  knowable  to  man;  by  dealing  (to  put  the  same 

hearts.  But  they  have  been  mystics,  or  saints,  or  laborious  parish  priests,  or  sisters  of 
mercy,  or,  better  still,  laymen  and  laywomen  living  in  the  daily  round  and  the  common 
task  as  "friends  of  God"  and  therefore  as  friends  of  man— seldom  theologians  as 
theologians. 

As  one  contemplates  this  history  one  cannot  but  wish  that  its  sundered  elements  had 
somehow  been  united  :  the  Western  church,  the  Eastern  theology ;  the  Teutonic  races, 
the  Greek  mind.  But  with  whatever  regret  one  looks  upon  the  past,  one  must  still 
remember  that  in  its  course  is  a  hidden  wisdom  greater  than  our  own.  And  though 
Origen's  intellect  was  one  of  the  most  spacious  that  ever  has  existed  upon  the  earth ; 
though  he  loved  much,  and  his  heart  was  pure,  and  his  theology  also  was  therefore  pure— 
not  tainted  by  human  hatreds  nor  sophisticated  by  the  use  of  legal  conventions ;  yet  the 
history  decided  that  the  future  was  to  be  not  with  him  but  with  the  great  African  who 
was  passionate  in  sin,  passionate  in  piety,  passionate  in  devotion  to  the  church,  passionate 
in  maintaining  the  many  diverse  positions  to  which  his  subtle  intellect  was  led,  and  who 
mastered  the  mind  of  the  Western  generations  to  whom  it  was  not  given  to  respond  to  the 
unflawed  saintliness  which  was  the  character  of  Origen  nor  to  the  untroubled  and  con 
sistent  light  which  was  his  mind. 

But  if  the  theologians  of  the  past  are  to  be  of  real  service  to  us— and  they  can  be— 
we  must  walk  with  them  as  their  companions,  not  as  their  slaves.  Hence  it  is  not  the 
need  of  the  day  that  Origen  should  be  set  on  Augustine's  disputed  throne.  In  theology 
there  has  already  been  too  much  of  human  masters  and  of  their  schools.  The  world  of 
to-day  ought  to  be  occupying  itself— and  is  coming  more  and  more  to  occupy  itself— 
with  the  New  Testament,  and  with  that  Son  of  man  and  of  God,  of  whom,  and  of  whose 
work  upon  human  hearts,  it  is  the  value  of  the  New  Testament  to  be  a  record. 

7  81 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

thing  in  other  words)  with  the  question,  raised  naively  by  Socrates, 
almost  solved  by  Plato,  reinstated  for  modern  thinking  by  Kant, 
"  How  is  knowledge  possible  ?" 

But  when  this  point  of  view  is  reached,  and  this  insight  into  the 
essential  character  of  the  world's  order  gained,  the  endeavour  of 
reason  to  know  the  world  is  still  not  at  its  end.  For  what  we  have 
done  is  this:  we  have  found  man  partly  possessing,  partly  striving 
to  possess,  science  of  the  detailed  facts  and  laws  of  the  world ;  and  by 
inquiring  how  such  science  is  possible  we  have  gained  an  insight  into 
the  true  character  of  the  world  and  of  its  order.  But  that  at  once 
puts  upon  the  scientific  reason  the  obligation  to  turn  back  to  the  details 
of  the  world  and  to  endeavour  to  give  them,  in  the  light  and  under  the 
guidance  of  the  insight  just  referred  to,  their  higher  and  further 
interpretation.  In  other  words,  if  you  have  seen  that  there  is  a  divine 
plan  of  the  world,  logically  you  cannot  stop.  You  have  to  go  on  to  ask 
-  what  that  plan  is :  which  involves  nothing  less  than  to  ask  what  the 
place  is,  in  that  plan,  of  each  of  the  particular  parts  of  the  total 
system ;  of  each  law  of  nature ;  of  each  determining  condition  of  man's 
life;  of  each  great  era  and  decisive  event  in  history;  nay,  even  of 
each  decisive  feature  and  event  in  each  man's  individual  life. 

To  put  it  epigrammatically,  when  philosophy  reaches  its  goal  its 
work  is  still  not  finished.  The  movement  so  far  described,  the 
movement  from  the  multiplicity  of  the  facts  of  the  world  to  the 
eternal  nature  and  eternal  constitution  of  the  world,  might  be  called 
a  movement  from  the  circumference  to  the  centre.  But  when  the 
centre  is  gained,  philosophy,  whether  as  pure  science  or  as  a  prac 
tical  temper,  cannot  cease  from  its  labour.  From  the  centre  it  must 
return  to  the  circumference,  but  bearing  with  it  the  light  gained  at 
the  centre,  and  seeking  by  the  aid  of  that  light  to  comprehend  more 
truly  the  details  of  the  circumference.  It  must  attempt,  that  is  to 
say,  to  give  to  the  particular  facts  of  the  world,  the  particular  facts 
of  nature  and  of  history,  their  "  divine  interpretation " ;  must 
attempt  to  view  them  not  only  as  facts  to  be  described  and  classified, 
but  also  as  elements  or  factors  in  a  divine  and  rational  plan.  To 
use  an  ancient  terminology,  the  first  movement  of  philosophy  is 

82 


AND   THE   VISION    OP    GOD 

along  the  upward  way — the  6<5os  arco — but  as  soon  as  this  move 
ment  has  gained  a  vision  of  its  goal,  philosophy  must  turn  to  the 
downward  way — theotfos  narcso — and  return  to  the  world,  but  bring 
ing  with  it  a  new  light  for  the  understanding  of  the  world.1 

And  this  demand  is  intensified  from  another  side.  Do  not 
human  history  and  human  society  themselves  contradict  this  account 
of  the  essential  constitution  of  the  world  and  this  view  of  man's  his-/- 
tory  as  a  process  in  which  an  eternal  purpose,  divine  and  divinely 
rational,  is  being  realised?  When  human  society  and  human  history 
are  what  they  are,  so  wasteful  of  life,  so  filled  with  oppression  of  the 
weak  by  the  strong,  so  tainted  with  mean  and  hideous  vices,  so  con 
fused  and  doubtful  in  the  whole  struggle  of  good  with  evil,  how  can 
they  be  interpreted  as  a  process  in  which  a  divine  purpose  is  being 
realised  and  a  city  of  God  built  up: — a  city  of  God,  in  which  each 
member  becomes  all  that  he  has  it  in  him,  in  virtue  of  his  divine 
origin,  to  be;  and  in  which  the  achieving  of  the  good  by  one  con 
tributes  to  (or  rather,  in  its  measure  ts)  the  achieving  of  it  by  all? 

It  is  obvious  that  within  the  limits  of  an  essay  nothing  more  can 
be  done  than  to  indicate  in  the  most  summary  fashion  the  general 
situation  in  which  the  intellect  finds  itself  when  it  confronts  this 
immense — nay,  this  infinite — field.2  Such  an  indication,  may  be 
given  by  considering  three  points. 

(A)  To  begin  with  the  simplest  matter,  it  may  be  noted  that  the 
main  divisions  of  the  field  are  fairly  well  marked  out.  On  the  one 
side  stands  philosophy  of  nature;  not  simply  in  the  sense  of  an 

1  Such  a  demand  for  the  return  of  philosophy  or  theology  from  God  to  the  world,  is 
binding  upon  that  Idealistic  type  of  philosophy  whose  central  argument  was  indicated  in  the 
preceding  section .  And  it  is  thus  binding  because  that  philosophy,  setting  out  to  understand 
the  world,  finds  in  God  and  in  a  divine  plan  at  once  the  explanation  of  the  world  and  the 
truth  of  the  world.    But  the  other  type  of  philosophy  with  which  we  are  concerned  in 
this  book— the  philosophy  (or  theology,  or  religion,— for  it  is  all  three)  of  the  via  negativa 
—is,  it  will  be  understood,  not  subject  in  the  same  sense  to  this  demand.    For  the  essence 
of  its  method  is,  that  it  proceeds  from  the  world  to  God,  not  by  the  synthetic  movement 
of  Idealism,  but  by  denying  the  world  altogether.    Hence  for  it  there  can  be  no  return 
from  God  to  the  world  in  the  sense  indicated  above,  but  only  the  ineffable  mystic  rest  in 
God.    (Cf .  supra,  pp.  9,  10,  and  infra,  pp.  116-150 ;  215  seq. ;  274  seq.) 

2  But  it  should  be  understood  at  the  outset  that  both  the  intellectual  obligation  to  this 
task,  and  the  pressure  of  the  cruel  problems  which  intensify  it,  fall,  not  merely  upon  some 
special  type  of  philosophy,  but  upon  everything  that  can  be  called  Theism. 

83 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

inquiry  into  the  ultimate  and  essential  character  of  the  physical 
order;1  but  in  the  extended  sense  of  an  attempt  to  give  to  the  details 
of  that  order  their  "  divine  interpretation  " — their  interpretation  as 
A  parts  or  elements  in  the  total  divine  plan.  On  the  other  side  stands 
philosophy  of  history.  And  here  also  the  inquiry  is  not  in  the  simple, 
but  in  the  extended,  sense.  That  is  to  say,  the  question  at  issue  is 
not  simply  the  question  how  history  is  possible;  is  not  simply  the 
question  how  that  process  is  possible  in  which  man,  an  intelligent 
and  active  spirit,  lives  in  organic  union  with  the  material  order  and 
its  laws,  and  yet  devotes  himself  through  his  generations  to  the 
realising  of  spiritual  and  social  ideals,  and  so  makes  history.2  It  is 
rather  the  endeavour  to  see  the  stages  and  events  of  man's  past  history 
in  their  true  meaning  and  their  true  light  as  steps  in  the  divine  plan 
of  the  world. 

Each  of  the  two  may  be  said  to  begin  with  broad  and  general 
problems  and  to  advance  from  these  to  particular  problems.  The 
general  problems  are  closely  allied  to  the  elementary  and  primary 
argument  outlined  in  the  preceding  section;  and  can  be  pursued  by 
the  human  intellect  with  some  degree  of  scientific  success  and  profit. 
But  the  particular  problems  require  for  their  solution  a  minute  knowl 
edge  of  the  details  of  the  divine  plan,  not  attainable  in  any  such 
experience  as  that  of  man  upon  the  earth.  In  the  philosophy  of 
nature,  for  instance,  the  first  and  easiest  of  the  more  general  prob 
lems  arises  from  that  character  of  the  physical  order  which  more  than 
any  other  has  impressed  the  modern  mind:  the  unbroken  orderliness 
which  prevails  in  it,  the  unchangeableness  and  inviolability  of  its 
laws.  This  problem  indeed  takes  us  only  a  step  beyond  the  general 
Idealistic  argument  already  outlined;  the  conclusions  reached  in  that 
argument  suggest  at  once  both  the  rational  necessity  of  this  "con 
tinuity  "  of  the  material  order,  and  the  possible  limitations  of  it.  And 
that  from  whichever  side  one  views  the  spatial  world :  whether  (a)  as 
an  expression  of  the  divine  nature,  or  (ft)  as  one  of  the  media  by 
which  God  communicates  to  man,  and  develops  in  man,  man's  own 

1  For  that  inquiry  would  be  simply  a  special  application  of  the  general  and  elementary 
argument  outlined  above  in  §V. 

2  For  that,  once  more,  would  involve  simply  the  argument  of  §V. 

84 


AND   THE   VISION    OF    GOD 

mind.  From  the  former  point  of  view,  the  spatial  order  is  regarded 
with  reference  to  its  source;  and  appears  as  necessarily  sharing  in 
the  absolute  orderliness  and  rationality  of  that  source.  From  the 
latter  point  of  view  it  is  regarded  with  reference  to  its  end.  That 
end  is  the  development  of  reason  in  man;  and  the  medium  by  which 
reason  is  communicated  must  itself  have  rationality  and  the  orderli 
ness  of  rationality.  The  source  is  reason;  the  end  is  the  develop 
ment  of  reason ;  any  medium  employed  by  such  a  source  toward  such 
an  end  can  scarcely  be  other  than  a  systematic  embodiment  of  reason. 
It  is  perfectly  true  that  we  men  in  our  best  endeavours  struggle 
toward  ends  imperfectly  conceived ;  perfectly  true  that  the  best  means 
we  can  fashion  for  ourselves  do  not  fully  express  even  those  imperfect 
conceptions;  for  we  have  to  work  upon  materials  of  which  we  are 
not  as  yet  fully  (or  even  approximately)  masters.  But  God  is  under 
neither  limitation.  The  divine  ends  and  the  divine  media  and  instru 
ments.,  when  known  as  they  truly  are,  are  all  alike  expressions  of  the 
divine  nature.  There  is  a  limitation  indeed.  But  it  is  not  in  God. 
It  is  in  the  minds  of  us  men  who  are  seeking  to  apprehend  God. 

In  the  philosophy  of  nature,  then,  general  problems  of  this  sort 
are  not  hopeless.  But  beyond  them  lies  that  which  is  almost  hope 
less:  the  endless  range  of  particular  problems;  the  task  of  compre 
hending  the  place  and  meaning,  in  the  divine  plan,  of  each  particular 
law  of  nature  and  each  particular  stage  and  event  of  natural  being. 
In  this  (for  a  reason  presently  to  be  stated),  little  is  possible  to  us 
except  conjecture.  Such  conjectures  have  indeed  been  made — from 
Aristotle's  day  to  Schelling's ;  and  often  they  have  been  both  brilliant 
and  happy.  But  they  are  always  to  be  ranked  as  probability  or  as 
prophecy,  and  not  as  assured  insight  gained  in  the  court  of  the 
philosophic  reason  by  methods  appropriate  to  that  court. 

And  so  in  the  philosophy  of  history.  We  have  already  seen1  how 
upon  the  field  of  history  the  divine  mind  operates  upon  and  in  and 
through  the  human  mind;  how  to  the  human  mind  the  divine  mind 
imparts  ideas  and  energies  which  are  in  some  genuine  sense  repre 
sentatives  of  the  T&OS  eternally  present  to  God;  how  these  become 
operative  powers  in  human  history  and  lead  forward  upon  its  way, 

i  §V,  ad  fin. 
85 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

in  religion  and  morality,  in  art  and  science,  in  society  and  the  state, 
the  spiritual  development  of  mankind.  The  human  intellect  may 
?work  with  some  success  (in  Hegel  has  worked  with  some  success) 
in  tracing  broadly  this  growing  impartation  of  divine  ideas  through 
the  main  stages  of  history — Oriental,  Greek,  Roman,  Mediaeval, 
Renaissance  and  Reformation,  eighteenth  century,  French  Revolu 
tion  and  its  era.  But  when  we  pass  on  to  ask  the  exact  "  divine 
interpretation"  of  each  particular  event,  it  must  be  said  (again  for 
a  reason  to  be  stated  presently)  that  we  are  going  beyond  the  limits 
of  the  knowledge  that  is  possible  upon  the  earth.  In  such  matters 
7  we  must  be  content  for  the  present  to  live  by  faith,  and  by  that  illu 
mination,  poetic  or  prophetic,  which  to  men  of  faith  is  not  denied. 

(B)  But  when  this  statement  has  been  made,  it  is  necessary  as 
a  matter  of  fairness  to  remind  ourselves  of  the  fact  which  was  stated 
near  the  beginning  of  the  present  section :  namely,  that  the  endeavour 
itself  is  a  legitimate  endeavour  of  the  scientific  reason.  And  that 
not  merely  in  the  sense  that  its  problem  can  be  stated  without 
absurdity  or  self-contradiction;  but  in  the  sense  that  science  must 
advance  to  it  or  remain  radically  incomplete.  It  lies  directly  upon 
the  road  along  which  science  advances  to  the  knowledge  of  the  world; 
it  not  only  forms  an  integral  stage  of  the  journey  of  science,  it  is  the 
last  and  culminating  stage.  It  is  absolutely  necessary  to  the  com 
pleteness  of  the  scientific  knowledge  of  the  world,  absolutely  necessary 
to  that  penetrating  and  thoroughly  articulated  knowledge  of  the  world 
which  it  is  part  of  the  business  of  reason  to  acquire.  And  this  last  and 
culminating  stage  the  scientific  intellect  must  somewhere  and  some 
time  enter  upon,  unless  it  is  to  turn  aside  from  its  work  of  knowing 
the  world  as  the  world  truly  is.  Nay,  more  than  this  must  be  said. 
Not  the  scientific  intellect  merely,  but  the  total  soul  of  man  must 
sometime  and  somewhere  enter  upon  (or  at  any  rate  progress  for  ever 
toward)  an  experience  of  this  type,  unless  it  is  to  turn  away  from  its 
true  goal — that  union  with  reality,  that  union  with  God,  in  which 
faith  becomes  one  with  reason,  and  perfect  activity  is  guided  by 
perfect  science. 

And  however  remote  such  a  consideration  as  that  may  appear, 
any  philosophical  writer  whose  speech  is  English  ought  resolutely  to 

86 


AND   THE   VISION    OF    GOD 

insist  upon  it.  For,  at  the  point  now  in  question,  the  sober  and  prac 
tical  genius  of  the  Anglo-Saxon  race  turns  instinctively  away  froim/ 
the  further  investigations  of  philosophy  to  the  practical  life. 
"  Enough,"  the  men  of  that  race  instinctively  say,  "  of  this  too  proud 
and  too  daring  journeying  of  the  reason  into  eternity.  Once  we  are 
assured  that  modern  science  of  nature  does  not  take  away  from  us 
the  vision  of  God  and  of  the  (  far-off  divine  event '  which  is  His  pur 
pose,  but  on  the  contrary  confirms  by  its  very  existence  that  vision, 
we  will  turn  again  to  the  field  to  which  we  properly  belong,  to  the 
practical  life."  This  is  the  native  and  characteristic  attitude  toward 
philosophy  of  the  genius  of  England,  as  it  speaks  through  those  of 
her  sons  who,  for  the  solution  of  the  intellectual  difficulties  that  beset 
their  moral  and  religious  devotion,  have  found  themselves  compelled 
to  go  to  the  schools  of  philosophy.  In  one  sense,  indeed,  the  men 
who  embody  that  genius  have  no  philosophy;  their  traditional 
"  school,"  the  school  of  Locke  and  the  Mills,  stands,  as  a  philosophy, 
at  no  great  remove  from  being  the  sorriest  thing  under  heaven.  But  { 
in  a  greater  sense,  they  have  philosophy:  they  have  the  philosophic 
mind — the  feeling  for  eternity,  the  sense  for  the  reasonableness  of 
things  and  for  ordering  life  in  accordance  with  that  reasonableness. 
But  this  philosophic  mind  they  have  expressed  in  their  own  way: 
not  in  technical  writings,  nor  in  system-making;  but  in  something 
better,  in  customs  and  institutions,  in  the  concrete  deed  rather  than 
in  the  abstract  word.  The  majestic,  yet  reserved  and  moderate,  eleva 
tion  of  the  prayers  of  their  great  church;  the  ancient  peace  of  their 
churchyards ;  the  mingled  dignity  and  simplicity  of  their  family  life ; 
their  mighty  works  of  war  4ind  of  peace,  of  commerce  and  of  justice, 
done  throughout  all  the  world: — these  are  the  works  of  their 
philosophy. 

Such  a  national  character  is  not  a  thing  to  be  lamented.  On  the 
contrary,  no  man  can  live  his  life  with  integrity — the  inchoate  integ 
rity  possible  upon  the  earth — without  to  a  very  great  degree  turning 
in  that  fashion  from  those  "  further  investigations  of  philosophy." 
Yet  such  a  national  character  makes  it  all  the  more  necessary  to 
insist  upon  the  statement  just  made,  that  whether  with  reference  to 
the  scientific  intellect  merely,  or  to  the  whole  nature  of  man,  that 

87 


THE    STUDY    OP    NATUKE 

further  stage  of  philosophy  must  somewhere  and  sometime  be  entered 
upon.  For  while  the  English  are  right  in  feeling  that  reason 

^embodied  in  institutions  is  a  greater  thing  than  rational  insight 
expressed  in  words,  yet — if  for  the  moment  a  Canadian  may  lay  aside 
the  restraint  due  from  him  and  speak  with  the  freedom  of  an  Eng 
lishman  at  home — they  run  a  double  danger.  In  the  first  place,  they 
are  in  continual  danger  of  sinning  against  the  spirit  of  science. 
And  no  power  upon  the  earth — whether  it  be  the  genius  and  charac 
teristic  temper  of  a  great  people,  or  the  proud  spirit  of  ecclesiastical 
theology — can,  without  self-destruction,  permanently  repudiate  the 
scientific  spirit,  or  permanently  oppose  it,  or  permanently  draw  a 
line  and  say  that  thus  far  it  shall  come  and  no  further.1  But  in  the 
second  place,  they  are  exposed  to  a  still  greater  danger  in  the  very 
field  of  their  strength — the  field  of  the  practical  life.  Alike  in  their 
institutions  and  in  their  conduct,  obstinate  unreason  and  authority 
without  intelligence  too  easily  secure  a  footing;  even  when  they  are 
saved  by  the  stubborn  and  half-instinctive  devotion  to  righteousness 
which  is  their  better  angel,  they  are  almost  lost  again  for  lack  of 
devotion  to  wisdom.  They  labour  hard  in  all  quarters  of  the  earth, 
performing  the  tasks  laid  upon  them  by  that  wisdom  of  the  world 
which  compels  all  the  peoples  to  its  service.  But  they  labour  blindly, 
in  obedience  rather  to  practical  instincts  and  to  their  tenacious  and 
masterful  hearts,  than  to  clear  visions  of  the  enlightened  intelligence ; 
and  so  they  achieve  great  things,  but  in  their  greatest  works  make 
themselves  often  the  fools  of  fate  rather  than  its  intelligent  servants. 
They  load  upon  their  shoulders  burdens  from  all  the  ends  of  the 

.  earth,  and  so  accomplish  the  works  of  the  world-spirit;  but  seldom  is 
any  vision  of  its  purpose  in  their  eyes,  seldom  the  joy  of  its  free 
service  in  their  hearts.  Doggedly  and  masterfully  and  blindly  they 
struggle  forward,  animated  by  a  spirit  that  is  mixing  itself  with  time 
and  leading  the  centuries  to  a  goal  beyond  the  horizon;  but  even  in 
thus  playing  their  part  and  fulfilling  their  great  vocation,  they  too 
often  forget  to  be  the  sons  of  the  hidden  wisdom  and  remain  only  its 
strong  slaves.  They  serve  God,  but  "  know  it  not " ;  they  work  His 

i  The  intellectual  spirit  that  England  needs,  if  her  genius  is  to  do  justice  to  itself,  is 
the  intellectual  spirit  of  Origen— or  of  her  own  forgotten  son,  Cudworth. 

88 


AND    THE   VISION    OF    GOD 

works,  but  look  not  upon  His  face.  God  fulfils  Himself  through 
their  labours;  but  they  themselves  stand  in  constant  danger  of  being 
exiles  from  God. 

(C)  But,  this  being  once  for  all  understood,  we  can  return  with 
clear  consciences  to  the  fact  with  which  we  are  at  this  point  specially 
concerned:  namely,  that  the  achievement  of  this  ultimate  goal  of 
science  is  beyond  our  present  powers,  and  beyond  the  horizon  of  our 
present  life.  If  achieved  by  us  at  all,  it  must  be  through  some  such 
development  of  our  capacities  of  reason  as  only  a  life  to  come  can 
afford.  Why  this  is,  and  what  the  loss  or  gain  of  it  for  us  men  is, 
may  be  seen  by  considering  two  points. 

(1)  The  inquiry  whose  course  was  outlined  in  the  preceding  sec 
tion  was  an  inquiry  into  the  ultimate  nature,  the  true  character,  of 
the  world.  The  conclusion  was  that  the  "  material  order "  is 
really  a  spiritual  system,  or  rather  a  factor  in  a  spiritual  system; 
that  the  world  has  its  source  in  a  divine  and  eternal  reason;  that 
there  is  a  divine  plan  of  the  world.  That  conclusion  was  gained  by 
the  reason  moving  easily  and  securely  through  an  elementary  and 
absolutely  simple  argument.  So  that  it  is  a  conclusion  both  easy  and 
safe  ;  no  man  who  has  once  really  comprehended  the  facts  and  argu 
ments  which  lead  to  it  can  well  cease  from  holding  it  in  some  form. 
But  what  we  have  now  come  face  to  face  with  is  something  very 
different.  It  is  no  longer  the  question,  What  is  the  true  nature  of 
the  world  ?  It  is  rather  the  question,  The  truth  of  the  world  con 
sisting  in  a  divine  plan,  how  are  we  to  interpret  each  of  the  facts  and 
events  of  our  present  world  as  elements  in  that  plan?  And  that  is  a 
problem  as  difficult  to  the  human  intellect  in  its  present  condition 
as  the  other  is  easy.  For  let  it  be  considered  what  it  involves  to  state 
the  exact  place  and  meaning  of  any  one  element  of  a  great  system  in 
the  total  plan  of  that  system.  It  involves  knowing  the  system  in  all 
the  completeness  of  its  detail.  Only  so  can  you  exactly  estimate  the 
place  of  any  one  detail  among  all  the  others.  And  to  the  extent  that 
your  knowledge  falls  short  of  that  kind  of  completeness,  to  that 
extent  is  your  interpretation  of  the  place  and  meaning  of  particular 
facts  and  events  conjecture  rather  then  science,  faith  rather  than 
knowledge.  It  may  be  most  brilliant  and  most  happy  conjecture; 

89 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

the  soul  of  man  may  apprehend  the  meaning  of  the  soul  of  the  world, 
even  as  some  most  fragmentary  mirror  in  the  remotest  of  the  stellar 
spaces  may  receive  and  reflect  the  ray  of  the  central  sun;  and  so  the 
conjecture  may  even  rise  to  the  level  of  such  a  faith,  of  such  a 
prophetic  interpretation  of  history,  as  a  wise  and  good  man  might 
very  rightly  be  willing  to  build  his  life  upon.  But  for  all  that,  to  the 
extent  to  which  the  total  plan  in  the  particularity  of  its  detail  is  not 
known,  such  interpretation  of  particular  facts  remains,  as  was  said, 
probability  rather  than  certainty,  conjecture  rather  than  science,  faith 
rather  than  knowledge.  And  the  extent  to  which,  upon  the  earth, 
we  are  thus  ignorant  of  the  "  total  plan  in  the  particularity  of  its 
detail,"  may  be  seen  by  considering  a  single  fact :  in  the  present  life 
we  move  among  beginnings;  that  which  is  to  come  after,  only  in  the 
light  of  which  can  these  beginnings  be  seen  in  their  full  significance, 
is  hidden  from  our  direct  acquaintance. 

But  if  this  is  so,  what  ought  we  to  do  with  regard  to  philosophy  of 
nature  and  philosophy  of  history  in  this  more  extended  sense?  Shall 
we  throw  them  summarily  overboard  as  endeavours  merely  and  simply 
hopeless?  To  a  question  of  this  sort  many  will  give,  instantly  and 
decidedly,  an  affirmative  reply.  But  the  men  whose  opinion  in  such 
a  matter  is  best  worth  having  will  be  held  back  from  that  summary 
procedure  by  one  consideration.  It  is  well  for  the  human  race  to  be 
kept  mindful  how  great  a  thing  its  endeavour  to  know  the  world 
really  is.  Hence  it  is  well  that  in  each  great  intellectual  era  there 
should  be  men  leading  the  forlorn  hope  of  science  into  the  field  now 
in  question;  men  great  enough  to  compel  respect  for  themselves  and 
their  work.  Indeed,  each  of  the  three  great  intellectual  eras  has  had 
such  men.  In  particular,  the  three  men  whose  names  have  already 
been  mentioned  together — Aristotle,  Aquinas,  Hegel — were  such  men. 
Each  worked  his  way  to  ultimate  principles,  and  then  in  the  light  of 
those  principles  proceeded  to  survey  all  the  provinces  of  experience; 
and  thus  attempted  to  form  all  the  science  of  his  day  into  its  "  encyclo 
paedia."  And  in  connection  with  this  there  is  one  specially  notable 
point.  One  of  the  three — Aquinas — was  no  solitary  prophet  of  the 
comprehensive  spirit  of  philosophy  to  a  gainsaying  age.  He  was  a 
philosopher  because  of  his  age,  and  in  his  philosophy  reflected  the 

90 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

temper  of  it.  And  the  instructive  thing  is  that  the  same  compre 
hensive  and  organising  spirit  which  led  the  thinking  of  the  age  to  its 
culmination  in  an  encyclopaedic  philosophy,  led  to  something  equally 
great  on  the  practical  side.  It  led  to  a  partial  success — partial  of 
necessity,  but  probably  greater  than  at  any  time  since  has  been 
achieved — in  dealing  with  that  practical  problem  with  which  the 
whole  life  of  humanity  upon  the  earth  is  a  wrestle;  the  problem, 
namely,  of  working  out  a  social  order  in  which  every  man  has  a  place 
— a  definite  station  with  definite  duties.  Just  because  from  this 
questing  of  the  intellect  into  eternity  we  are  about  to  turn  back  to  the 
"  every-day  practical  life,"  we  ought  all  the  more  keenly  to  remember 
that  the  age  in  which  men  walked  most  confidently  in  those  fields  of 
philosophy  from  which  we  are  here  turning  away,  was  an  age  in 
several  most  important  respects  greater  than  our  own  in  this  very 
matter  of  practical  achievement. 

(2)  But,  in  the  second  place,  if  reason  enters  here  upon  a  field 
where  for  most  of  us  the  footing  is  precarious  and  where  only  an 
elect  few  can  do  work  which  compels  respect ;  if  the  work  of  philosophy 
changes  at  this  point  from  the  gaining  of  assured  insight  by  an  argu 
ment  of  absolute  simplicity,  to  the  laborious  and  uncertain  work  of 
interpreting  details  whose  total  scheme  is  not  open  to  our  vision : — so 
also  at  this  point  does  man's  need  of  rational  insight  change.  If  we 
may  believe  that  there  is  a  divine  plan  of  the  world,  a  plan  rational^ 
and  righteous,  then  it  is  no  long  step  and  no  illogical  step  to  the 
belief  that  if  we  organise  our  lives  according  to  the  best  reason  and 
the  best  righteousness  open  to  our  vision  upon  the  earth,  we  shall  be 
putting  ourselves  upon  a  pathway  whose  end  will  be  the  organisation 
of  our  lives  according  to  the  reason  and  the  righteousness  of  the  city 
"  whose  pattern  is  laid  up  in  heaven."  For,  as  already  we  have  seen, 
the  divine  idea  does  not  dwell  apart  from  human  history.  The 
supreme  principle  of  the  divine  mind  is,  and  must  be,  the  supreme 
law  of  that  whole  activity  of  God  which  is  the  world  and  the  history 
of  the  world.  But  that  divine  idea,  as  also  we  have  seen,  does  not 
act  upon  human  history  like  a  mechanical  power  upon  material  bodies. 
It  acts  by  imparting  itself  to  men,  and  shaping  their  spirits,  and 
winning  them  to  itself;  thus  it  becomes  at  once  the  source  and  the 

91 


THE    STUDY    OF    JSTATUKE 

nourishment  of  all  development  of  reason  among  men  and  of  all 
human  effort  after  righteousness.  And  so  the  reason  and  the 
righteousness  that  men  have  so  far  been  able  to  grow  into  must  be 
looked  upon  as  at  once  the  result  of,  and  the  representative  of,  and 
the  pathway  toward,  the  reason  and  the  righteousness  that  are  perfect 
and  eternal.  And  if  this  be  true,  we  need  not  mourn  greatly  that  the 
exact  "  divine  interpretation  "  of  the  particular  events  of  history  and 
the  particular  facts  of  nature  is  hidden  from  us.  The  life  of  faith  is 
justified.  "  Assure  us,"  so  we  may  say,  "  assure  us  that  there  is  a 
divine  plan  of  the  world;  that  over  all  things  rules,  and  through  all 
history  operates  supremely,  an  eternal  spirit  who  is  living  reason  and 
living  righteousness.  Assure  us  that  the  ultimate  power  of  the  world 
is  the  perfection  of  that  goodness  after  which  we  struggle  so  imper 
fectly;  and  that,  therefore,  the  goodness  which  is  to  us  a  goal  far-off 
and  dimly  understood  is  in  truth  both  the  ultimate  reality  of  the 
world  and  the  immanent  law  and  '  hidden  wisdom  9  of  the  world's 
process — a  ( wisdom'  which  may  indeed  be  veiled  under  forms  hard 
in  the  extreme  for  such  a  creature  as  man  to  read,  and  may  indeed, 
in  its  clashes  with  the  '  creative  will ?l  of  man,  seem  cruel  to  its  own 
servants,  but  none  the  less  is  working  effectually  and  lovingly  toward 
its  goal.  Assure  us  that  the  world  is  not  in  its  real  constitution  a 
non-moral  order  which  cares  nothing  for  moral  and  rational  ends  and 
awaits  with  nature's  stern  patience  the  day  when  we  men  shall  have 
perished  and  '  all  things  shall  be  once  more  as  if  we  and  all  the 
labours  of  our  morality  and  of  our  religion  never  had  been  ' ;  but  that, 
on  the  contrary,  the  eternal  power  which  constitutes  the  conditions  of 
our  life  is  more  interested  than  even  we  ourselves  can  be  in  the  causes 
of  human  goodness ;  so  that  when  a  man  sets  himself  about  that  work 
to  which  the  present  state  of  the  human  race  incessantly  calls  everyone 
who  is  willing  to  hear — the  work  of  saving  men  from  the  evils 
without  them  and  within  them,  and  of  rousing  in  their  hearts  devotion 
to  the  causes  of  goodness — he  is  not  dashing  himself  against  an 
eternal  and  hopeless  barrier,  either  in  God  or  in  nature,  but  rather  is 
in  line  with  the  supreme  power,  the  supreme  law,  the  supreme  pur 
pose,  of  the  world. — Assure  us  of  these  things  and  we  will  fight  the 

i  T.  H.  Green,  Works,  Vol.  III.,  p.  278. 
92 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

battle  of  life,  if  not  in  the  strength  of  complete  knowledge,  at  any 
rate  in  the  strength  of  hope  and  of  faith.  We  will  not  lament  that 
after  a  certain  point  the  journeying  of  the  reason  into  eternity 
becomes  perilous  or  even  impossible.  At  whatever  point  the  check 
comes,  we  have  at  any  rate  learned  enough  to  enable  us  to  labour  in 
faith,  devoting  ourselves  to  the  causes  of  present-day  reason  and 
present-day  righteousness,  and  trusting  that  in  so  doing  we  are  making 
ourselves  organs  and  instruments — nay,  sons  and  fellow-workers — of 
the  eternal  righteousness.  It  matters  little — at  any  rate  it  will  not 
drive  us  to  rebellion  or  to  despair — that  concerning  the  exact  and 
eternal  meaning  of  each  detail  we  are  for  the  present  in  the  dark. 
We  are  willing  enough  to  fight  for  a  time  in  the  dark,  or  on  a  border- 
ground  between  light  and  dark,  if  only  we  can  assuredly  believe  that 
the  order  of  the  world  which  sets  all  these  conditions  of  our  life  is 
in  ultimate  analysis  a  reasonable  order,  and  that  the  supreme  power 
of  the  world  is  really  favourable  to  us  in  our  struggle  after  the  good 
ness  of  ourselves  and  of  our  fellows.  If  only  we  can  know  that 
nature  and  history  have  a  '  divine  interpretation/  we  will  turn  back 
to  the  labours  and  the  battles  of  the  practical  life,  willing  enough  that 
the  full  details  of  that  interpretation  should  for  a  time  be  hidden 
from  our  eyes." 

VII. 

Such,  then,  in  a  brief  outline  of  its  elements,  are  the  stages  and 
conclusions  of  the  greatest  and  safest  argument  which  man  has  been 
able  to  work  out  concerning  the  nature  of  the  world  and  the  meaning 
of  his  life  in  it;  an  argument  which  had  for  the  first  of  its  world- 
prophets  Plato,  but  owes  its  specifically  modern  formulation  and  con 
duct  to  an  insight  won  partially  and  laboriously  in  old  age  by 
Immanuel  Kant.  The  ultimate  explanation  of  the  world  and  of  our 
life  (so  it  finds)  is  an  eternal  spirit  and  an  idea  or  purpose — the 
Good — which  that  spirit  is  realising  in  the  process  of  the  world. 
Eeality — the  universe — is  a  society  of  spirits;  that  eternal  spirit  and 
the  lesser  spirits  in  whom  the  eternal  spirit  reproduces  himself.  The 
existence  of  "  material "  objects  means  their  being  present  to  that 

93 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

eternal  self-consciousness  and  their  having  a  place  in  the  system  of 
that  divine  thought.  Our  sciences  of  nature,  with  the  mathematical 
and  physical  sciences  which  logically  precede  the  "natural  sciences/' 
are,  when  viewed  from  below,  an  entry  of  ours  into  the  content  of 
the  eternal  mind;  when  viewed  from  above,  an  impartation  of  that 
mind  to  us,  by  which  our  own  minds  are  developed ;  are,  in  one  word, 
a  divine  impartation  meeting  a  human  effort.  Morality,  in  the  true 
form  of  its  idea,  is  the  devotion  of  us  men  to  the  service  of  that  divine 
idea  or  purpose  which  is  being  realised  in  the  history  of  the  world, 
but  which,  as  we  have  seen,  makes  its  way  toward  its  own  realisation 
not  by  acting  mechanically  upon  men,  but  by  winning  them  as  free 
spirits  to  its  service.  And  religion,  when  it  becomes  truly  itself,  is 
the  greater  whole  of  which  such  morality  is  a  part ;  is  the  eif ort  after 
unity,  in  affection,  in  character,  in  activity,  with  the  eternal  spirit 
who  is  the  subject  of  the  world.  So  that  the  history  in  time  of  the 
universe,  when  seen  as  it  truly  is,  is  a  process  in  which  an  eternal 
spirit  realises  an  eternal  purpose  by  imparting  himself : — reproducing 
himself  in  spirits  that  are  finite,  and  free  in  so  far  as  their  finitude 
permits;  and  winning  those  spirits  to  himself;  and  communicating 
himself  to  them  both  intellectually  and  morally,  not  only  through 
the  visions  of  poets  and  prophets,  but  also  through  every  effort  of  the 
man  of  science  after  knowledge  and  of  the  good  man  after  goodness; 
and  so  making  possible  the  attainment  of  that  City  of  God  which  is 
the  r^Aos"  of  all  his  action  and  therefore  the  supreme  law  and  imma 
nent  principle  of  the  whole  process.1 

These  are  conclusions  of  philosophy;  and  therefore,  in  stating 
them  the  language  of  philosophy  has  been  used.  But  it,  like  all  tech 
nical  language,  has  a  certain  reticence ;  so  that  it  may  be  advisable  to 
re-state  in  one  or  two  sentences  of  more  familiar  tone,  the  conclusion 
which  has  just  been  summed  up.  To  say,  then,  that  the  universe  is 
a  society  of  spirits,  an  eternal  spirit  and  the  lesser  spirits  in  whom 
he  has  under  limitations  reproduced  himself,  is  to  say  that  the 

i  This  might  be  summed  up  technically  by  saying  that  one  and  the  same  thing  is  the 
supreme  principle  alike  of  Being,  and  of  Knowledge,  and  of  Morality  and  Religion.  It  is 
his  clear  insight  into  this  and  his  steady  insistence  upon  it,  that  make  Plato  the  greatest 
teacher  in  the  schools  of  philosophy ;  and  the  one  most  salutary  to  the  divided  and  dis 
tracted  modern  mind.  (Cf.  Philosophical  Lectures  and  Remains  of  Richard  Lewis 
Nettleship,  1st  ed.,  Vol.  II.,  p.  218  seq.) 

94 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

universe  is  a  family,  and  that  the  relation  between  its  members  and 
the  eternal  spirit  who  is  at  once  their  source  and  their  home  is  the 
relation  of  sonship  and  fatherhood.  And  that  Father  is — not  merely 
has,  but  is — all  rational  and  moral  perfection.  That  is  to  say,  reason, 
righteousness,  and  love,  are  at  the  heart  of  things;  are  the  immanent 
law  both  of  the  constitution  of  the  world  and  of  the  process  of  the 
world.  And  the  reason,  the  righteousness,  and  the  love,  which  are 
thus  at  the  heart  of  the  world,  are  one  thing  and  not  three  things ;  for 
each  in  order  to  be  itself  has  to  be  the  other  two.  Eeason  without 
love  and  righteousness  would  be  merely  a  hard  logic.  Eighteousness 
devoid  of  reason  and  love  would  be  but  an  arbitrary  and  iron-clad 
law,  such  as  would  intensify  all  evil  and  thus  defeat  its  own  aim/  And 
love  without  righteousness  and  reason  would  be  no  love  at  all,  but  some 
thing  quite  contrary  to  love — a  weak  and  foolish  indulgence  working 
continual  injury  to  its  own  object.  In  God  reason,  righteousness,  and 
love,  are  one  thing  ;x  and  in  their  undivided  unity  they  are  at  once  the 

i  When  one  has  apprehended  this,  it  is  at  first  with  anger,  but  presently— when  the 
long  upward  struggle  of  humanity  through  many  different  levels  of  thinking  toward  the 
light,  has  made  its  appeal  to  one's  heart— with  a  feeling  very  different  from  anger,  that 
one  remembers  the  way  in  which  Western  theology,  after  the  Reformation  as  well  as 
before,  frequently  dealt  with  the  divine  attributes.  That  theology  was  developed  in  a 
legal  and  political  atmosphere.  Naturally  enough  it  took  for  granted  the  legal  view  of 
the  relation  of  God  to  the  world ;  it  used  many  specific  legal  conceptions,  taken  from 
Roman  or  Teutonic  law  ;  what  is  still  more,  in  thinking  about  God  it  retained  the  habits 
of  the  lawyer's  mind— its  acuteness,  its  argumentativeness,  its  delight  in  convenient  but 
unreal  distinctions,  its  tendency  to  rely  upon  serviceable  arbitrary  conventions  instead  of 
seeking  pure  truth  for  its  own  sake.  Hence  it  was  easy  for  this  theology  to  rend  apart  the 
unity  of  the  divine  nature ;  easy  for  it  almost  to  view  the  divine  nature  as  a  battle-ground 
of  conflicting  attributes— separating  sharply  the  righteousness  from  the  love  of  God, 
then  virtually  hypostatising  these  abstractions,  so  as  to  set  them  over  against  each  other 
and  thus  make  an  opening  for  a  forensic  theory  of  atonement.  But  theology,  so  far  as  it 
imprisons  itself  in  this  framework  of  abstractions,  does  not  know  God  ;  though  the  men 
who  made  the  theology  may  have  loved  Him.  To  come  at  the  matter  from  another  angle 
—one  very  relevant  to  the  mind  of  the  church  at  the  present  hour— such  theology,  though 
it  held  the  Bible  in  great  reverence,  did  not  know  the  Bible.  It  was,  in  the  correct  though 
not  in  the  sectarian  use  of  the  term,  un-Evangelical ;  it  did  not  know,  and  was  not  based 
upon,  the  mind  of  Jesus  as  recorded  in  the  Gospels.  For  in  the  Gospels  what  Jesus 
continually  insists  upon,  throughout  His  work  of  revealing  and  establishing  the  Kingdom  of 
God,  whose  King  is  a  Father,  is  His  own  unity  with  the  Father.  In  His  whole  mission  to 
the  world,  He  is  one  with  the  Father  ;  that  mission  and  that  work,  therefore,  express  the 
mind  and  attitude  of  the  Father ;  they  are  not  a  forensic  expedient  for  changing  that 
mind  and  attitude.  Jesus,  to  use  St.  John's  great  expression,  is  the  Word,  in  whom  the 
character  of  God  and  His  mind  toward  man  are  spoken  forth  :  and  that  puts  out  of  court 
for  ever  the  idea  that  the  mission  of  Jesus  to  the  world  either  represented  or  made  possible 
a  change  in  the  mind  of  the  Father  toward  men.  Hence  it  is,  that  as  Biblical  Theology— 

95 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

nature  of  God  and  the  law  of  every  divine  act;  and  therefore  the 
immanent  principle  of  that  order  of  the  universe  which  the  divine 
activity  constitutes. 

These  conclusions  and  the  argument  which  leads  to  them  have  in 
the  preceding  sections  been  stated  as  matters  that  belong  simply  to  the 
courts  of  the  reflective  reason.  As  such,  they  represent  what  any 
scientific  inquiry  represents — the  intellect  of  man  at  its  legitimate 
work  of  trying  to  understand  the  world  it  lives  in.  And  that  attempt 
needs  no  special  defense  or  apology.  To  the  endeavour  to  understand 
his  world  man  is  called  by  the  laws  and  powers  of  his  own  nature ;  so 
that  the  effort  itself  is  not  merely  a  legitimate  one,  but  is  an  integral 
and  essential  part  of  that  activity  by  which  man  develops  his  own 
being,  and  comes  truly  to  be  man,  and  so  fulfils  his  divine  vocation. 

But  the  greatest  of  all  the  masters  who  have  worked  in  those 
courts  of  the  reflective  reason  would  not  have  left  the  matter  upon 
that  footing.  To  Plato,  as  his  whole  life  and  the  whole  body  of  his 
writings  at  every  point  make  manifest,  philosophy  meant  a  temper 
and  a  character  as  well  as  an  activity  of  the  scientific  intelligence. 
And  it  meant  these  three,  not  as  standing  apart,  but  as  joined 
together  in  that  indissoluble  unity  in  which  each  shares  the  nature 
of  the  others  and  each  contributes  to  the  perfection  of  the  others.  It 
meant  a  life  in  which  philosophy,  as  an  activity  and  a  vision  of  the 
intellect,  has  passed  over  into  the  "  philosophic  mind,"  and  that  mind 
has  become  the  guide  of  conduct.  Whether  with  Greeks  or  with 
moderns,  the  sounder  any  man  is  in  character,  the  more  unwilling  he 
is  that  truth  and  life  should  stand  apart.  The  integrity  of  his  charac 
ter  compels  him  to  seek  for  unity  in  his  life ;  compels  him,  if  he  has 
apprehended  a  profound  view  of  life,  to  seek  to  transmute  that  view  of 
life  into  life  itself.1 

the  science  which  studies  the  types  of  Biblical  teaching  from  their  own  point  of  view  and 
upon  their  own  scale  of  internal  proportion— makes  its  way  in  the  thought  of  the  church, 
and  compels  the  church  more  and  more  to  return  to  the  mind  of  its  Founder,  those 
forensic  structures  which  it  was  the  delight  of  the  political  and  legal  mind  of  the  West  to 
build  in  the  courts  of  theology  cease  to  be  either  the  home  or  the  prison-house  of  the  souls 
that  seek  to  enter  upon  their  true  relationship  to  God. 

i  In  this  no  name  can  rank  with  Plato's.  Yet  we  men  of  the  West  ought  with  piety  to 
recall  the  name  of  one  who  helped  to  found  philosophy  among  ourselves— the  brave 
Roman  to  whom  philosophy  meant  not  only  knowledge,  but  uprightness  in  action  and 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

And  not  only  is  this  essential  to  integrity  of  personal  character. 
It  is  demanded  also  by  the  nature  of  truth  simply  as  truth.  Here, 
indeed,  we  are  brought  to  a  point  about  which  misapprehensions 
cluster ;  misapprehensions  so  passionate  that  it  is  advisable  to  set  down 
both  sides  of  the  question. — (1)  Philosophy  does  not  create  life.  For 
philosophy  is  primarily  science.  It  is  an  effort  to  understand.  It  no 
more  professes  to  create  the  world  whose  ultimate  nature  it  seeks  to 
apprehend,  or  the  life  whose  meaning  it  inquires  after,  than  (for 
instance)  chemistry  professes  to  create  those  elements  and  those  rela 
tions  of  elements  which  are  the  object  of  its  investigations.  The  soul 
of  man  is  by  its  original  nature  scientific,  artistic,  practical;  and  in 
its  practice  capable  of  morality  and  religion.  Hence  the  life  of  man 
is  a  life  scientific,  a  life  artistic,  a  life  practical,  a  life  moral,  a  life 
religious.  This  is  the  given  object,  and  what  philosophy  does  is  to 
attempt  to  understand  it ;  is  to  attempt  to  apprehend  the  meaning  of 
that  life,  and  the  nature  of  the  world  in  which  it  is  lived  and  by 
which  its  conditions  are  set.  The  man  who  urges  that  philosophy 
cannot  create  religion,  and  then  finds  in  that  the  ground  for  an 
habitual  dislike  of  philosophy  or  a  passionate  warfare  against  it, 
simply  misapprehends  the  whole  situation.  And  such  a  misappre 
hension,  it  ought  to  be  understood,  is  a  revelation  of  the  man  himself. 
But  (2)  philosophy  can  be  of  use  in  guiding  life  where  life  already 
exists.  For  truth,  simply  by  being  itself,  has  power  over  the  soul. 
To  make  truth  merely  cold  and  dead;  to  deny  that  the  visions  of 
reason  can  afford  any  awakening  or  inspiration  to  the  moral  and 
religious  nature;  to  regard  light  as  nothing  and  heat  as  everything; 
to  set  science  and  life,  knowledge  and  goodness,  truth  and  religion, 
radically  apart : — this  is  to  shiver  man's  nature  into  blind  and  crippled 

fortitude  in  affliction,  and  who  handed  on  his  lesson  to  be  a  consolation  to  many  a  saddened 
heart  in  the  troubled  West.  Philosophy,  so  Boethius  learned  and  taught,  is  the  love  and 
pursuit  of  that  wisdom  which  is  the  quickening  mind  and  primeval  principle  of  things ; 
is  in  some  sort  a  fellowship  with  it,  so  that  the  intelligent  mind  is  at  once  illuminated  by 
it  and  drawn  back  into  it.  So  that  philosophy,  in  being  the  pursuit  of  wisdom,  is  a  pursuit 
of  divinity.  For  that  wisdom  which  is  the  eternal  principle  of  the  world  imposes  the 
worthiness  of  its  own  divinity  upon  all  the  souls  that  occupy  themselves  with  it,  and 
brings  them  to  the  force  and  purity  of  their  own  true  nature  ;  and  thus  arises  not  only 
a  truth  of  speculations  and  thoughts,  but  also  a  holy  chastity  of  acts.  (See  the  finely 
sympathetic  account,  and  specially  the  analysis  of  the  De  Consolatione,  in  Maurice.  The 
foregoing  sentences  are  from  Maurice's  statement  of  the  conception  of  philosophy  found 
in  the  first  dialogue  In  Porphyrium. ) 

8  97 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

fragments,  instead  of  recognising  that  the  true  power  and  perfection 
of  that  nature  consist  in  a  unity  in  which  each  part  contributes  to  all 
the  others.  The  man  who  habitually  does  it,  and  imagines  that  he  is 
serving  religion  thereby,  may  mean  well.  But  it  ought  to  be  pointed 
out  to  him  that,  to  the  extent  to  which  this  tendency  dominates  him 
and  is  not  counteracted  by  other  and  sounder  things  in  his  work,  to 
that  extent  he  is  making  himself  really  a  valuable  servant  to  only  one 
kind  of  religion — that  which,  having  no  truth  in  it,  wishes  to  have 
nothing  to  do  with  truth.1 

We  can  see  then,  to  return  to  a  statement  of  a  moment  ago,  how 
from  both  sides — from  philosophy  as  intellectual  truth,  from  the 
integrity  of  character  which  forbids  men  to  let  truth  and  life  stand 
apart — there  is  a  compulsion  to  the  attempt  "  to  transmute  one's 
*  view  of  life  into  life  itself."  Indeed  it  is  only  for  the  men  who 
recognise  that  compulsion,  or  rather  it  is  only  in  such  men,  that 
philosophy  does  its  true  and  full  work.  And  to  attempt  to  gain  some 
hint  or  glimpse  of  how  in  such  men  philosophy  turns,  through  the 
"  philosophic  mind,"  back  into  life,  is  the  last  thing  that  we  have  here 
to  do. 

It  can,  indeed,  be  only  a  glimpse.  But  it  is  worth  while  to  try  to 
gain  even  a  glimpse.  For  what  the  philosophic  mind  brings  to  our 
life,  is  the  habit  of  regarding  and  valuing  the  goods  of  life  from  the 
point  of  view  of  that  eternal  purpose  which  man's  life  is  intended  to 
realise.  And  never  was  the  need  of  that  habit  so  great,  whether  on 
the  part  of  the  leaders  of  society  or  on  the  part  of  the  general  body 
of  its  members,  as  now.  For  the  resources  of  society,  both  intellectu 
ally  and  still  more  in  the  subjection  of  natural  powers  to  man's  use, 
are  greater  than  ever  before.  But  owing  to  the  assertion,  throughout 
>the  whole  of  society,  of  the  individual  in  his  private  and  selfish 
interests,  those  resources  are  most  wastefully  used.  A  few  specially 

i  Of  course,  in  thinking  of  truth  as  a  guide  of  life  and  an  inspiration  for  life,  the  fact 
noted  in  the  introduction  must  be  kept  in  mind.  There  is  a  tendency  in  us  all  to  overlook 
the  radically  important  distinction  between  abstract  and  concrete  truth.  A  man  of 
science,  for  instance,  who  deals  with  some  one  aspect  of  reality  in  strict  isolation  from  the 
others,  easily  forgets  the  abstract-ness  of  his  own  special  science ;  easily  is  tempted  to 
think  that  its  principles  give  the  final  account  of  the  world  and  of  our  life.  Thus  we  get 
those  "  premature  and  hasty  "  world-views  of  which  Materialism  and  the  mechanical 
view  of  the  world  are  examples.  (Cf.  supra,  pp.  4,  5.) 

98 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

skilful  or  fortunate  men  possess  them — frequently  to  their  own  inner 
evil — in  large  measures;  while  to  many  they  are  only  very  scantily 
available,  or  not  at  all.  And  the  solutions  so  far  wrought  out  are 
tainted  by  the  evil  itself  which  they  seek  to  cure;  for  they  are  only 
those  partial  and  bitter  solutions  which  separately  organised  classes 
are  able  to  win  and  to  maintain  at  the  point  of  the  sword. 

In  the  first  place,  then,  the  men  in  whom  philosophy  has  become 
the  philosophic  mind  have  learned  the  first  and  most  fundamental  of 
all  practical  lessons.  They  have  learned  what  the  true  business  of 
life  is.  Stated  on  its  positive  side,  it  is  the  winning  of  men's  hearts 
to  those  causes  of  goodness  (goodness  as  including  "  all  science,  all 
art,  every  virtue  and  all  perfection")  which  are  the  causes  of  God, 
and  in  the  service  of  which  men  at  one  and  the  same  time  fulfil  their 
divine  vocation  and  come  to  be  truly  themselves.  It  is  only  as  taking 
its  appropriate  place  in  that  endeavour  that  any  resource  of  nature 
which  man  has  mastered,  or  any  power  of  his  own  mind  or  heart  or 
hand,  is  rightly  used. 

But  secondly,  in  what  they  have  learned  concerning  the  world,  such 
men  have  not  only  an  illumination  with  regard  to  what  the  business 
of  life  is.  They  have  also  in  it  certain  great  sources  of  strength  and 
of  steadiness  as  they  turn  to  the  actual  performance  of  that  business 
of  life.  To  begin  with,  they  have  what  for  want  of  some  better  name 
one  must  call  the  strength  of  hope — the  strength  of  a  faith  which 
reason  justifies.  For  they  have  learned  that  however  Manichsean  the 
present  appearance  of  our  life  may  be,  there  is  no  Manichseism  at  the 
eternal  heart  of  things.  They  have  learned  that  there  is  no  eternal 
moral  dualism  in  the  universe,  such  as  can  set  to  the  endeavour  of 
good  men  after  goodness  (not  their  own  individual  goodness  merely, 
but  the  goodness  of  all  their  race)  a  hopeless  limit  or  a  final  defeat. 
For  what  they  have  seen  is  this :  that  the  legitimate  and  inevitable 
onward  course  of  the  scientific  reason,  the  legitimate  and  inevitable 
onward  course  of  that  attempt  to  know  the  world,  of  which  physical 
and  natural  science  is  one  stage,  ethical  and  social  science  another 
stage,  brings  us  at  last  to  the  vision  of  a  God  who  is  over  all  and  in 
all,  and  by  union  with  whom  men  may  enter  upon  courses  of  minis 
tration  to  their  fellows,  which  shall  be  checked  by  no  eternal  limit 

99 


THE    STUDY    OF    JSTATUBE 

nor  defeated  by  any  eternal  barrier.  For  to  Him  goodness  is  of 
absolute  value;  it  is  the  end  for  which  He  constituted  and  keeps  in 
existence  all  His  worlds.  And  as  His  end  can  be  defeated  by  no  other 
god  greater  than  He,  still  less  can  it  be  defeated  by  any  change  in 
Himself  or  in  His  attitude  toward  men.  At  no  point  whether  in 
this  world  or  in  any  world,  can  He  either  forget  the  end  for  which 
He  made  the  world,  or  lay  aside  the  character  which  makes  Him  love 
and  welcome  the  effort  of  His  creature  after  goodness.  He  cannot 
at  any  point  lay  aside  the  character  in  which  reason  and  righteousness 
and  love  are  one;  cannot  at  any  point  turn  away  for  ever  from  good 
men  in  their  struggle  for  the  world's  goodness,  and  thenceforward 
return  to  them  for  ever  the  answer :  Hitherto  shall  you  come,  but  no 
further;  and  here  shall  all  power  of  self-sacrifice,  and  all  passionate 
striving  of  love,  and  all  devotion  to  the  extension  of  the  Kingdom  of 
God  and  of  good,  eternally  be  stayed.  On  the  contrary,  it  is  His  very 
nature,  as  the  source  and  home  and  end  and  ultimate  power  of  the 
world,  at  once  to  make  possible  and  to  respond  to  for  ever,  that 
prayer  which  not  only  ascends  from  the  depths  of  man's  sin  and  from 
his  extremities  of  conflict  and  of  defeat,  but  is  also  the  normal  and 
habitual  "  human  cry  " : 

Cast  me  not  away  from  thy  presence; 
And  take  not  thy  holy  spirit  from  me. 

So  that  these  men  go  forward  into  life — into  life  as  life  is,  with  its 
anguish  of  burdened  and  fragmentary  and  broken  labours,  its  still 
profounder  anguish  of  evil  triumphant  and  good  causes  beaten  back — 
knowing  that  even  if  the  worst  come  to  the  worst  the  ultimate  truth 
of  the  world  still  forbids  any  paralysis  of  despair.  They  have  that 
same  source  of  unfathomable  strength  which  the  Stoics  and  the  men 
of  Geneva  had :  they  know  that  they  are  devoted  to  the  cause  which  in 
all  history  is  supreme  and  final,  that  they  are  in  line  with  the  ultimate 
law,  the  eternal  and  present  purpose,  of  the  world;  so  that  even 
though  they  seem  to  the  view  of  this  world  to  be  defeated  and  to 
perish,  yet  really  the  universe  is  with  them  and  the  stars  in  their 
courses  are  fighting  for  them.1  And  in  addition  to  this,  they  have 

i  As  Wordsworth  knew ;  and  the  knowledge  was  part  of  his  poetical  being.  The 
sonnet  to  Toussaint  L'Ouverture  brings  it  to  very  pointed  expression  ;  but  it  is  always  in 
Wordsworth's  mind. 

100 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

what  the  Stoics  had  only  in  part  and  the  men  of  Geneva  scarcely 
allowed  themselves  at  all — a  vision  of  the  essential  rationality  of  the 
supreme  power.  And  with  essential  rationality,  essential  kindliness; 
for  while  eternal  reason  may  seem  to  us  men  an  austere  thing, 
teaching  by  the  discipline  of  changeless  laws,  and  bringing  without 
fail  to  every  human  soul  the  consequences  of  its  own  deeds,  yet  in  the 
ultimate  truth  of  things  such  reason  is  with  love,  and  love  with  such 
reason,  interchangeable;  and  the  form  of  their  co-operant  action  is 
righteousness. 

And  so  these  men,  in  so  far  as  they  are  able  to  make  their  way  of 
life  respond  to  what  they  know  about  the  world,  bring  to  the  battle  of 
life  a  certain  grave  and  unyielding  courage,  a  certain  patient  steadi 
ness.  They  have  looked  upon  eternal  ideas,  which  are  greater  realities 
than  all  the  "  hard  facts  "  and  all  the  "  actualities  "  of  to-day,  and 
which  are  at  last  to  subdue  to  themselves  these  facts,  and  all  facts, 
and  to  make  them  obedient  servants  in  a  realm  where  the  eternal  ideal 
is  at  once  the  real  and  the  soul  of  all  reality.  Men  who  have  seen  such 
things,  and  are  able  to  rejoice  in  them,  are  not  likely  to  be  cowards. 
And  eyes  that  gaze  habitually  into  eternity  are  wont  to  be  steady  eyes 
and  to  impart  to  the  soul  behind  them  the  steadiness  of  the  eternal 
objects  upon  which  habitually  they  are  fixed.  "  God  is  patient,"  so  a 
great  saying  runs,  "  because  He  is  eternal."  The  things  that  drive  us 
to  the  edge  of  despair — the  good  that  we  see  so  clearly,  but  cannot 
bring  to  pass ;  the  warfare  of  the  brute  facts  of  the  world  against  that 
in  us  and  in  our  fellows  which  is  gentlest  and  touched  most  with 
heavenly  light;  the  strange  failures  and  defeats  that  here  shatter  a 
good  cause  or  yonder  blast  into  deformity  an  individual  life;  'the 
unspeakable  meannesses  and  cruelties  that  are  practised  by  the  strong 
and  the  fortunate  against  the  weak  and  the  defenseless — meannesses 
and  cruelties  of  which  the  world  is  full,  and  in  presence  of  which  a 
man's  indignation  scarcely  can  keep  itself  from  falling  to  wild  anger ; 
above  all,  the  lives  that  are  born  in  evil,  and  pass  to  the  life  to  come 
never  having  known  anything  but  evil: — these  things  do  not  mean 
that  God  and  the  good  have  a  power  over  against  them  able  to  defeat 
them.  Nor  do  they  mean  that  God  is  absent  from  the  world,  and 
that  we  must  give  up  the  ancient  teaching  that  "  God  worketh  until 

101 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

now."  They  mean  the  patience  of  a  vast  design.  In  presence  of  them 
the  man  who  is  devoted  to  goodness  has  to  remember  that  in  all  such 
things  there  is  ultimately  but  one  question;  it  is  not  a  question  of 
death  or  of  time;  it  is  a  question  of  God.  And  with  God  there  is  no 
failure ;  it  would  be  easier  for  the  heavens  and  the  earth  to  pass  away 
and  all  things  to  come  to  nothingness,  than  for  any  single  act,  done 
in  any  age  for  righteousness'  sake  or  for  love's,  to  fail  of  its  due 
result. 

Such  a  "  philosophic  mind  "  is  not  the  first  power  of  life.  Love 
and  devotion  are  the  first  powers  of  life — and  the  last.  And  love  and 
devotion  can  work  in  the  dark ;  with  blind  eyes  they  have  done  their 
most  heroic  deeds.  But  soon  or  late  their  very  nature  leads  them  to 
this  calmness  and  patience  of  minds  that  see  present  things  in  the  light 
of  the  eternal.  For  soon  or  late  their  nature  leads  them  to  look  upon 
God;  and,  looking  upon  Him,  they  learn  to  see  things  under  the 
form  of  eternity.  And  then  their  "  last  enemy "  is  overcome ;  for 
from  the  point  of  view  of  eternity  our  enemies  and  our  tyrants  are 
seen  to  be  our  friends.  But  the  best  way  to  understand  this  is  to 
state  it  in  the  terms  of  a  more  ancient  conception.  Our  life  is  a 
wrestle  with  a  power  not  ourselves ;  a  stern  and  unfailing  power  that 
with  no  shadow  of  weakness  goes  straight  onward  in  its  way,  over 
the  hearts  of  men,  over  the  plans  of  men,  over  the  prayers  of  men. 
Men  of  science  are  content  nowadays  to  call  it  Law,  but  in  their  older 
language  they  called  it  Necessity;  ancient  poets  called  it  Fate.  To 
human  life  it  is  present  in  many  forms :  sometimes  as  an  iron  limita 
tion  ;  sometimes  as  a  foundation  to  be  built  upon ;  sometimes  as  a  task 
master  bringing  to  men  labours  that  they  would  not  have  chosen  and 
responsibilities  such  as  appall  the  soul;  always  as  a  law  to  be  obeyed 
and  fulfilling  itself  with  absolute  exactness  upon  the  disobedient.  It 
can  never  be  evaded :  nor  can  any  man  overcome  it  save  by  submitting 
to  it  and  taking  it  as  the  law  of  his  own  being.  But  such  unity  of  the 
individual  soul  with  the  necessity  that  operates  in  the  world  and  in 
the  history  of  the  race,  is  doubly  difficult  to  attain.  The  very  capaci 
ties  that  make  us  human  set  us  beyond  that  easy  and  perfect  obedience 
to  necessity  which  is  within  the  power  of  the  leaf  or  the  tide  or  the 
star;  and  furthermore,  however  willing  our  hearts  might  be,  its 

102 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

operation  in  history  proceeds  with  so  vast  a  movement  that  as  it 
works  upon  the  individual  life  it  manifests  rather  its  crushing  power 
than  its  law  or  its  goal.  And  so  we  dash  ourselves  against  it  with  that 
pain,  that  blind  and  hopeless  agony,  that  mad  indignation  as  against  a 
fundamental  injustice  in  things,  which  has  made  its  cry  heard  in 
human  literature  from  the  beginning  until  now.1 

But  in  so  far  as  a  man  is  able  to  see  the  world  and  our  life  "  under 
the  aspect,  as  it  were,  of  eternity,"  he  looks  upon  necessity  at  its 
source;  and  looking  upon  it  there,  sees  it  in  its  true  nature.  It  is 
eternal  and  rational  and  righteous ;  for  it  is  the  earthward  aspect  of  the 
divine  reason,  the  form  which  the  divine  action  takes  on  to  eyes  that 
are  not  yet  able  to  read  it  clearly.  Unfailingly  and  unfalteringly  it 
"  reaches  from  end  to  end,  sweetly  and  strongly  ordering  all  things." 
Only  when  viewed  from  below  does  it  appear  mechanical  and  without 
a  soul.  Its  vast  plan  we  cannot,  indeed,  grasp  in  detail.  But  we  can 
know  its  nature;  we  can  know  that  Fate  is  the  wisest  of  all  things, 
and  that  in  that  "  history  of  the  world  "  which  is  "  the  world's  court 
of  judgment "  the  decisions  which  ultimately  are  given  need  no 
reversal. 

And  the  man  who  knows  this,  knows  that  necessity  is  the  disciplin 
arian  of  the  soul,  and  is  therefore  his  friend.  He  knows  that  necessity 
is  the  source  at  once  of  the  greatness,  the  difficulty,  and  the  security, 
of  the  good  man's  life.  It  is  the  source  of  the  difficulty  of  that  life; 
for  it  brings  the  soul  to  desperate  passes — it  makes  its  journey  long 
and  stern  and  its  conversion  a  lifelong  process  in  which  each  upward 
step  leads  to  the  unveiling  of  greater  issues  and  the  opening  of  wider 
struggles.  It  is  the  source  of  the  greatness  of  that  life;  for  it 
is  by  his  long  struggle  with  necessity — the  struggle  in  which 
victory  is  won  only  by  apprehending  the  wisdom  behind  that  inexorable 
face,  and  submitting  to  it,  or  rather  growing  up  into  it — that  man 
comes  to  be  man,  that  the  greater  powers  of  his  nature  are  developed, 
the  greater  achievements  of  his  spirit  wrought  out.  For  it  is  upon  a 
system  of  necessity  which  no  individual  will  can  break  down  or  throw 
into  confusion,  that  all  orderly  labour,  mental  or  physical,  is  based; 
of  such  necessity  literature,  in  its  higher  forms,  strives  to  picture  the 

i  Cf.,  for  instance,  Butcher,  Some  Aspects  of  the  Greek  Genius,  2nd  ed.,  p.  145 seq. 

103 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

incidence  upon  life ;  science  is  a  study  of  its  ways  in  nature,  philosophy 
an  attempt  to  penetrate  to  its  real  character ;  the  theology  which  does 
not  deal  with  it  may  indeed  be  happy,  but  is  happy  because  it  is  still 
a  child.  The  necessity  which  lies  beyond  the  control  of  the  individual 
will  and  is  "  the  hidden  wisdom  of  the  world  "  is,  in  fact,  the  form 
which  the  love  that  works  throughout  the  whole  process  of  the  universe 
assumes  in  order  to  become  the  schoolmaster  of  the  human  soul.1  And 
as  necessity  is  thus  the  source  of  the  difficulty  and  the  greatness  of 
the  good  man's  life,  so  is  it  also  the  source  of  its  security.  For  it  is  the 
last  law — and  the  first — of  necessity,  that  ultimately  the  fate  of  every 
soul  shall  be  an  absolutely  righteous  and  rational  fate — righteous  and 
rational  as  righteousness  and  reason  are  in  God.  In  the  end  no  soul 
that  lives  will  have  anything  of  which  it  can  rightly  complain ;  without 
possibility  of  error  every  man  will  come  at  last  to  his  own  place. 

And  in  addition  to  the  necessity  which  thus  is  present  in  nature 
and  history,  and  shapes  for  the  individual  the  unchangeable  conditions 
of  his  life,  there  acts  upon  the  good  man  a  necessity  of  a  different 
order.  It  is  that  moral  necessity  which  arises  out  of  the  very  char 
acter  of  human  life.  We  are  citizens  in  a  temporal  and  earthly  order. 
But  our  vocation  has  its  home  in  eternity,  and  in  its  demands  knows 
nothing  of  the  limitations  of  time.  So  that  to  the  good  man — to 
every  man  who  is  not  a  coward,  evading  the  demands  of  the  world 
upon  him — life  itself  is  a  continual  call  to  the  bearing  of  a  burden 
impossible  to  be  borne,  to  the  performance  of  duties  that  are  beyond 
man's  power.  What  ought  to  be  done,  again  and  again  we  cannot  do, 
or  more  often  can  do  only  in  part;  and  we  come  down  to  the  grave 
weary  men  who  have  struggled  hard  and  at  the  last  are  but  unprofitable 
servants.  But  the  insight  into  the  nature  of  that  other  necessity  sets 
this  also  in  the  true  light ;  like  the  other,  it  is  in  its  very  sternness  and 
oppression  the  ally  of  the  man  whose  soul  is  turned  toward  goodness. 
Here,  as  there,  when  we  enter  into  the  heart  of  what  seemed  a  power 
inexorable  and  indifferent,  what  we  find  is  the  deep  heart  of  a  friend 
— a  friend  too  wise  to  make  any  mistake,  too  kind  to  admit  even  the 
slightest  particle  of  weakness  or  indulgence  into  that  system  of  things 

i  One  cannot  pass  on  without  referring  to  the  noblest  of  the  modern  expressions  of 
this— that  contained  in  Tennyson's  In  Memoriam. 

104 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

which  is  the  framework  of  our  life.  If  man's  vocation  goes  beyond 
his  opportunities,  if  his  "  ought "  stretches  on  infinitely  beyond  his 
powers,  so  that  after  a  long  struggle  he  finds  himself  still  an  unprofit 
able  servant,  there  is  even  in  this  no  cause  for  lament  or  for  complaint 
of  injustice.  That  life  should  be  an  endeavour  to  overtake  a  vocation 
which  runs  beyond  human  powers  and  human  opportunities  is  better 
for  us,  is  infinitely  more  worthy  both  of  God  and  of  man,  than  that 
we  should  remain  untroubled  children  for  ever,  with  only  such  duties 
laid  upon  us  as  our  powers  are  adequate  to  perform.  Only  through  a 
life  so  constituted  and  through  such  struggle  can  children  of  time  and 
of  the  earth  rise  out  of  their  childhood,  and  enter  upon  their  inherit 
ance  and  their  true  being  as  citizens  of  eternity;  and  better  the 
breaking  of  the  heart  than  failure  from  that  citizenship. 

So  that,  in  the  presence  of  evil  and  of  necessity,  the  men  who  have 
passed  from  philosophy  to  the  philosophic  mind  are  like  soldiers  who, 
in  the  midst  of  some  long  struggle,  have  looked  through  the  struggle 
and  have  seen  behind  it  eternal  powers  and  eternal  destiny.  And  with 
that,  so  far  as  their  character  responds  to  their  knowledge,  their 
courage  takes  on  a  new  character;  to  the  old  stubborn  tenacity  which 
out  of  mere  manliness  could  not  yield,  there  comes  a  lofty  intellectual 
soul  of  vision  and  of  hope. 

But  this  new  order  of  courage  in  the  presence  of  evil  and  of 
necessity  is  only  a  single  aspect  of  what  the  soul  comes  to  be,  as  truth 
and  life  become  one.  Along  with  it  goes  another  quality  of  the  soul ; 
a  quality  less  stern  and  therefore  apparently  less  high.  But  really  it 
is  both  higher  and  more  difficult.  For  it  is  one  of  those  virtues  of 
comprehension  which  always  are  harder  of  attainment  than  the  virtues 
of  conflict.  It  is  what  may  be  called  the  virtue  of  catholicity;  the 
strength  and  steadiness  which  catholicity  of  mind  gives  to  a  man  in 
presence  of  the  contending  parties,  contending  interests,  contending 
solicitations,  of  the  world.  For  let  us  remember  once  more  what  the 
philosophy  here  in  question  has  to  teach  us,  both  about  the  business  of 
our  lives,  and  about  the  world  we  are  living  in.  The  constitutive 
principle  of  reality — so  it  teaches — and  therefore  the  condition  of  all 
knowledge  and  the  regulative  principle  for  all  conduct,  is  the  good. 
And  the  good  is  one ;  it  consists  in  a  perfect  society,  a  civitas  Dei,  the 

105 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE 

7  character  of  whose  individual  members  is  that  character  which  is 
already  and  eternally  real  in  God.  Furthermore,  it  is  (as  the  ultimate 
principle  of  the  divine  activity)  at  once  the  animating  purpose  and 
the  inner  unity  and  the  "  hidden  wisdom "  of  the  world.  The 
troubled  process  which  is  life  and  history  is  a  field  wherein  it  wins 
men  to  itself,  and,  by  imparting  itself  to  them  and  so  making  them 
truly  men,  works  out  its  own  realisation.  So  that  there  is  in  all  life 
and  in  all  history  one  supreme  object  for  the  devotion  of  all  men. 
It  is  only  as  being  a  stage  in  the  realisation  of  that  divine  idea,  it  is 

/  only  as  being  a  step  toward  the  bringing  into  being  of  that  civitas  Dei, 
that  any  duty  is  a  duty  at  all,  or  any  labour  worthy  of  being  done,  or 
any  cause  deserving  of  support,  or  any  institution  worthy  of  loyalty. 
At  all  times  and  in  all  places  and  for  all  men  that  divine  idea  is  the 
one  determination  of  the  path  of  duty.  It  therefore  is  the  one  object 
of  endeavour  that  is  truly  catholic;  the  causes  that  make  for  it  are 
the  only  truly  catholic  causes ;  devotion  to  it  and  to  those  its  causes  is 
the  one  true  catholicity;  and  the  man  to  whom  such  devotion  is  the 
supreme  and  organising  principle  of  life  is  the  one  true  catholic. 

This  does  not  mean  any  aloofness  from  life.  Nor  does  it  mean  that 
life  is  to  be  reduced  to  a  flat  monotony  of  devotion  to  an  indivisible 
One.  On  the  contrary,  as  many  as  are  the  capabilities  of  human  nature, 
so  many  are  the  pathways  of  the  divine  idea  toward  its  realisation. 
But  it  does  mean  that  there  is  eternally  in  God  an  end  or  good,  as  wide 
as  life,  which  is  at  once  the  constitutive  principle  of  the  world's  order, 

-  and  the  true  guide  and  goal  of  human  action:  and,  as  such,  is  the 
standard  of  judgment  for  all  human  causes  and  purposes  and  enthusi 
asms  ;  for  all  subjection  of  the  immortal  spirit  to  the  body ;  for  all  use 
of  the  resources  of  life  in  vain  display ;  for  all  sectarian  divisions ;  for 
all  that  political  and  social  selfishness  which  puts  individual  interest 
before  general  welfare ;  for  all  those  ideals  and  passions  and  ambitions 
which  set  men  apart  from  one  another,  and  break  the  unity  of  society 
in  church  and  state,  and  lead  to  the  oppression  of  man  by  man  or 
class  by  class. 

Something,  then,  such  as  this,  is  what  philosophy  means  when  it 
becomes  the  philosophic  mind.  But  what  has  been  said  is  only  a  hint. 

106 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

Other  qualities  of  that  mind  might  have  been  spoken  of;  its  willing 
ness,  for  instance,  to  recognise  the  presence  of  God — in  nature,  in  the 
movement  of  history,  in  those  great  lay  activities  and  virtues  which 
sometimes  the  religious  despise.  But  in  particular  one  thing — and 
that  the  most  important  of  all — which  might  have  been  dwelt  upon, 
has  not  been  dwelt  upon.  We  saw  that  the  universe  is  really  a  great 
family — a  society  composed  of  an  eternal  spirit  and  the  lesser  spirits 
in  whom  the  eternal  spirit  reproduces  himself,  for  whom  he  sets  a 
vocation,  and  to  whom,  in  science  and  in  art,  in  morality  and  in 
religion,  he  more  and  more  imparts  himself,  reconciling  them  to 
himself,  winning  their  hearts  back  to  himself,  and  by  that 
reconcilement  and  that  impartation  enabling  them  to  become 
truly  themselves.  But  such  a  view  of  the  universe  is  a  call  to 
personal  affection  and  personal  devotion,  and  to  all  the  energies  and 
powers,  to  all  the  passion  and  all  the  achievement,  of  such  devotion 
and  such  affection.  And  if  that  view  of  the  universe  be  philosophy,  i 
the  philosophic  mind  must  in  the  true  form  of  its  idea  be  the  same  as 
the  religious  mind — the  mind  which  in  the  activities  and  energies  of 
a  supreme  affection  seeks  to  become  more  and  more  at  one  with  God 
and  with  that  purpose  of  God  which  is  the  ultimate  law  alike  of  the 
world  and  of  man's  being.  But  of  that  no  mention  has  been  made,  in 
the  attempt  to  give  the  reader  some  glimpse  of  what  philosophy  is 
when  it  passes  over  into  the  philosophic  mind,  and  transmutes  itself 
into  life  and  temper  and  character,  and  so  does  its  full  work.  And 
for  that  silence  there  was  a  reason.  It  is  only  in  some  world  to  come, 
when  the  philosophic  mind,  and  the  moral  mind,  and  the  religious 
mind,  have  all  risen  to  the  true  form  of  their  idea,  that  we  shall  be 
able  to  see  them  as  one  and  the  same.  For  our  present  world  the  fact 
stands  that  such  affection  as  is  here  in  question  is  commonly  roused 
in  men  in  a  way  which  does  not  begin  in  intellectual  vision.  Speaking 
broadly  and  allowing  for  a  few  striking  exceptions,  the  work  of 
philosophy  in  this  respect  has  been,  not  so  much  to  rouse  in  men  the 
love  of  God,  as  to  do  a  certain  work  for  those  who  already,  and  by 
other  of  the  divine  agencies  of  reconciliation,  have  been  led  to  make 
that  love  the  supreme  principle  of  the  practical  life: — namely,  to 
clear  their  eyes,  and  to  give  an  intellectual  soul  to  the  vision  of  their 

107 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATUKE 

faith,  and  to  cast  upon  their  world  and  upon  their  path  through  it  a 
broad  illumination  of  rational  light. 

We  must  say,  then,  that  philosophy,  in  its  greater  and  clearer 
forms,  leads  us  to  see  that  the  love  of  God  should  be  the  supreme 
principle  of  life.  But  we  must  also  say  that  philosophy  in  those 
greater  and  clearer  forms  is  the  possession  of  a  few.  What  is  needed 
for  the  whole  wide  race  is  something  that  in  human  form  and  human 
affection  can  lie  close  at  man's  heart,  that  can  illuminate  with  personal 
example  all  the  events  and  relations  of  his  life,  that  can  be  received 
by  the  simplest  and  the  weakest,  in  a  way  not  possible  to  that  which  is 
primarily  an  endeavour  of  the  intellect  and  a  construction  of  the 
scientific  reason. 

And  in  this  connexion  there  is  in  the  history  of  philosophy  a  most 
remarkable  fact.  There  came  an  age  in  which,  for  many  high  and 
pure  souls,  philosophy  had  no  choice  but  to  undertake  the  guidance  of 
life ;  in  fact  the  need  was  so  profound  that  philosophy,  for  the  sake  of 
the  practical  life,  had  even  to  set  about  the  task  of  purifying  religion.1 
In  the  greatest  of  her  masters  philosophy  rose  to  meet  the  call.  The 
intellectual  and  moral  splendour  with  which  the  task  was  discharged, 
they  most  admire  who  know  the  story  best.  Indeed  the  man  must  be 
very  narrow  in  sympathies,  or  very  ungrateful,  who  can  look  with 
merely  fault-finding  eyes  upon  what  philosophy  was,  and  upon  what 
philosophy  did,  as  she  tried  to  meet  that  awful  need  of  the  spirit 
which  already  in  Plato's  day  was  descending  over  Greece.  But  pre 
cisely  in  that  day,  precisely  when  philosophy,  called  to  bear  a  burden 
too  great  for  her,  summoned  all  her  powers  and  rose  to  her  most  starry 
splendour,  with  the  genius  of  prophecy,  the  genius  of  art,  the  genius 
of  science,  labouring  together  in  her  courts  and  at  her  command — 
precisely  then  it  was  that  her  spokesmen  wrote  in  her  records  a  double 
cry :  the  cry  for  a  revelation  beyond  his  own ;  and  the  high  resolve  of 
the  natural  soul  to  make  the  best  of  the  stern  situation,  so  long  as  that 
higher  revelation  was  denied  by  heaven  to  men.  "  I  will  tell  you  my 
difficulty/' — so  Plato  makes  Simmias  to  speak  in  the  Phaedo2 — "  and 
Cebes  will  tell  you  his.  I  feel  myself  (and  I  daresay  that  you  have 

i  Cf.  Republic,  377  E  seq. 
2  85  C.  (tr.  Jowett).—  Socrates,  it  will  be  remembered,  is  about  to  die. 

108 


AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

the  same  feeling)  how  hard  or  rather  impossible  is  the  attainment  of 
any  certainty  about  questions  such  as  these  in  the  present  life.  And 
yet  I  should  deem  him  a  coward  who  did  not  prove  what  is  said  about 
them  to  the  uttermost,  or  whose  heart  failed  him  before  he  had 
examined  them  on  every  side.  For  he  should  persevere  until  he  has 
achieved  one  of  two  things :  either  he  should  discover,  or  be  taught  the 
truth  about  them ;  or,  if  this  be  impossible  I  would  have  him  take  the 
best  and  most  irrefragable  of  human  theories,  and  let  this  be  the  raft 
upon  which  he  sails  through  life — not  without  risk,  as  I  admit,  if  he 
cannot  find  some  word  of  God  which  will  more  surely  and  safely  carry 
him." 

Plato  did  not  know  that  for  the  desire  of  which  he  had  been  a 
prophet,  there  was  to  come  a  fulfilment  more  genuine  than  he  had 
dreamed :  not  in  a  great  argument,  sounding  onward  in  a  voyage  that 
few  could  follow;  but  in  a  life  that  had  dwelled  where  Plato  desired 
the  philosophic  soul  to  dwell — in  the  bosom  of  eternity — and  came  to 
man  with  a  kindliness,  with  a  simplicity  and  directness  of  humanity, 
with  a  "  loveliness  of  perfect  deeds,"  which  every  burdened  man,  and 
every  little  child, 

And  those  wild  eyes  that  watch  the  wave 
In  roarings  round  the  coral  reef, 

can  apprehend.  And  Plato  did  not  know  that,  soon  after  that  life 
passed  from  among  men,  He  who  had  lived  it  was  to  be  apprehended 
"  under  the  form  as  it  were  of  eternity "  by  two  great  masters  of 
life  and  of  thought.  The  one  declared  that  in  Him  the  universe 
consists;  that  He  is  the  supreme  law  of  the  whole  history  of  man 
and  of  the  whole  system  and  process  of  the  world.  The  other,  using 
the  same  word  that  Plato  had  used,  declared  that  He  was  the  Word, 
the  divine  Word,  which  reveals  the  eternal  to  men  and  gives  them 
such  vision  as  man  needs  of  that  divine  idea  which  is  at  once  the  law 
of  the  world's  order,  and  the  condition  of  all  knowledge,  and  the  good 
for  all  human  endeavour.  He  is  the  manifestation  of  the  ultimate 
God;  and  in  Him  is  summed  up  the  law  of  the  world;  for  these  two 
things  are  one,  each  involving  the  other.  But  these  great  offices  He 
discharged  upon  the  earth,  not  in  the  form  of  some  blinding 

109 


THE    STUDY    OF    NATURE   AND    THE    VISION    OF    GOD 

majesty  which  could  have  taught  us  only  our  own  nothingness,  but  as 
a  man,  who  in  purity  of  heart  and  in  simplicity  lived  for  others ;  lived 
for  us  all,  and  from  the  Galilaean  fields  and  from  His  cross  speaks 
still  to  the  hearts  of  those  for  whom  He  lived.  And  as  His  appeal 
comes  to  us,  some  of  us  look  upon  Him  early,  and  love  Him,  and 
walk  in  His  way.  But  others  of  us  go  out  proudly  and  in  strength 
to  our  work,  and  suddenly,  we  know  not  how,  are  in  the  grasp  of 
powers  greater  than  ourselves,  and  come  to  the  end  of  the  day  broken 
men;  and  beneath  the  gathering  shadow,  with  the  house  of  life  in 
ruins  about  us,  turn  to  Him,  and  receive  from  Him  hope  that  rises 
above  the  scene  of  our  defeat,  and  the  gift  of  peace,  and  power  at  last 
to  overcome  the  world. 


110 


THE  METAPHYSIC  OF  SPINOZA 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA. 
I. 

IN  our  effort  to  apprehend  that  reality  of  things  which  is  also  the 
truth  of  our  life,  new  insights  come  but  slowly  to  full  possession  of 
themselves.  A  new  method,  a  new  category,  a  new  point  of  view, 
seldom  comes  to  its  right  in  a  single  man  or  a  single  generation. 
Through  many  men  a  school  labours  toward  a  goal  not  clearly  appre 
hended  at  the  beginning;  a  goal  from  which  the  founders,  could  they 
have  seen  it,  might  have  turned  in  dismay.  But  the  method  more  and 
more  does  justice  to  itself;  the  tendency  enters  more  and  more  fully 
into  its  own  meaning;  and  at  last  the  man  arises  in  whom  the  school 
finds  at  once  its  culmination  and  its  end.  The  system  of  thought 
which  such  a  man  leaves  behind  him  has  more  than  the  purely 
scientific  interest.  It  marks  a  finished  stage  in  one  great  side  of  that 
human  pilgrimage  through  time  which  is  history;  it  takes  on  the 
dignity,  the  grave  and  moving  interest,  of  a  concluded  chapter  of 
human  fate.  A  given  tendency  in  man's  long  endeavour  to  know 
himself  for  the  thing  he  is  and  to  shape  his  life  according  to  that 
knowledge,  has  been  carried  to  its  utmost  limit;  a  given  method 
employed  to  its  utmost  power.  All  that  this  tendency,  all  that  this 
method,  can  do,  it  has  done.  It  began  as  best  it  could.  It  worked 
its  way  forward  through  its  stages,  clarifying  itself  and  learning  to 
be  true  to  itself  as  it  advanced.  And  now  it  has  assumed  its  final 
shape;  has  made  manifest  at  last  the  meaning  which  was  in  it. 
Henceforward,  in  that  "  history  of  the  world  "  which  is  "  the  world's 
court  of  judgment,"  it  abides,  an  achieved  fact,  standing  face  to  face 
with  its  opponents  and  awaiting  verdict. 

There  have  been  three  chief  instances  of  this  in  modern  thought. 
One  stands  strangely  in  the  midst  of  its  school.  David  Hume  carried 
to  their  logical  conclusion  the  point  of  view  and  the  method  of 

9  113 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

English  empiricism;  and  by  doing  so  showed  their  hopeless  inade 
quacy  to  the  task  of  understanding  how  our  experience  can  be  what 
it  actually  is.  But  Hume,  with  all  his  acuteness  of  intelligence,  did 
his  work  as  a  man  whose  first  love  was  fame,  not  as  a  man  who  had 
devoted  himself  to  the  service  of  ultimate  truth;  and  after  his  day 
the  school,  unable  to  learn  the  lesson  that  looks  out  from  his  pages, 
went  on  with  the  old  watchwords,  the  old  point  of  view,  the  old 
method.  The  second  instance  is  a  work  vaster  in  design,  nobler  in 
spirit.  In  his  encyclopedic  view  of  the  embodied  reason  which  is  the 
structure  and  the  history  of  the  world,  Hegel  carried  forward  to  its 
due  use  as  a  world-principle  that  synthetic  character  and  activity  of 
intelligence  which  Kant  in  his  own  rigid  and  cramped  way  had 
brought  forward  in  inquiring  into  the  possibility  of  human  knowl 
edge.  But  the  third — earliest  of  the  three  in  time  and  moving  in 
the  atmosphere  of  a  more  primitive  type  of  thought — was  in  many 
respects  the  most  striking  of  all.  Once  in  the  history  of  the  Western 
world,  and  once  only,  the  leaders  in  thought  and  science  broke  delib 
erately  through  the  continuity  that  links  together  the  successive 
generations,  and  turned  with  disgust  and  anger  from  the  results 
accumulated  by  the  labour  of  the  ages  gone.  In  dealing  with  the 
highest  problem  of  science,  they  would  return  to  the  very  beginning 
and  by  the  use  of  a  new  method  would  comprehend  nature  and  pene 
trate  to  the  truth  concerning  man.1  Such  was  the  Cartesian  attempt. 
But  the  full  significance  of  the  Cartesian  method  and  the  Cartesian 
categories  was  not  worked  out  by  Descartes  himself.  Geulincx,  and 
the  great  name  of  Malebranche,  mark  further  stages  in  the  process 
by  which  the  endeavour  initiated  by  Descartes  entered  into  possession 
of  its  own  meaning.  But  the  man  to  whom  it  was  given  to  complete 
this  process — the  man  who  spoke  the  last  word  of  this  philosophical 
school,  and  made  clear  to  the  world  for  ever  the  final  outcome  and 
meaning  of  the  Cartesian  way  of  attacking  the  ultimate  problems  of 
science— was  Benedict  de  Spinoza,  a  solitary  man  who  was  pure  in 
heart  and  cared  nothing  for  wealth,  or  social  position,  or  fame,  but 
loved  truth,  and  for  its  sake  was  willing  to  be  driven  from  his 
father's  house  and  to  earn  a  sternly  simple  fare  by  grinding  lenses. 

i  Cf.  supra,  p.  59. 
114 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

It  is  true  that  the  Cartesians  were  not  aware  of  this  relation  of 
Spinoza  to  their  school ;  true  that  Spinoza  himself  was  scarcely  aware 
of  it.  Malebranche  is  ready  to  anathematise  Spinoza;  and  Spinoza 
occasionally  protests  in  very  sharp  terms  against  this  or  that  particu 
lar  doctrine  of  Descartes.  But  that  does  not  alter  the  case.  All 
these  men  of  thought  were  seized,  as  Kuno  Fischer  so  aptly  reminds 
us,  "  by  the  powers  of  whom  it  is  said  nolentem  trahunt " ;  though 
they  themselves  did  not  know  it,  they  were  all  labouring  at  a  single 
task,  and  moving  through  the  different  stages  of  a  single  journey. 

f; '  \  II. 

This  lonely  man  it  was,  then,  who  spoke  the  last  word  of  that  type 
of  thinking  with  which  the  modern  world  began  when  it  revolted 
from  the  mediaeval  and  proceeded  to  build  anew  the  house  of  life  and 
of  thought.  That  last  word  he  spoke  so  resolutely  that  the  world  was 
enabled — or  rather  compelled — to  pass  on  to  those  other  thoughts  in 
the  midst  of  which  we  men  of  to-day  live.  So  that  Spinoza  is  one  of 
the  founders  of  the  present-day  world ;  and  yet  he  stands  far  from  our 
daily  companionship.  He  helped  to  make  us  what  we  are;  and  yet 
to  most  of  us  he  seems  unspeakably  remote,  a  solitary  and  monu 
mental  name,  a  vast  but  far-off  power. 

But  there  is  another  interest,  if  possible  one  still  deeper,  connected 
with  the  name  of  Spinoza.  In  thought — and  in  life — there  is,  as 
already  we  have  seen,1  a  division  profounder  than  that  into  historical 
stages  and  schools;  there  is  a  distinction  of  fundamental  tendencies, 
an  antithesis,  simple,  radical,  primitive,  which  at  once  underlies, 
and  expresses  itself  through,  the  differences  of  the  schools;  the  dis 
tinction,  namely,  between  the  thought  (and  the  religion)  which  in 
finding  God  finds  the  light  and  truth  of  the  world,  and  that  which,  to 
find  God,  leaves  the  world  behind.  And  what  gives  to  Spinoza  this 
second  and  profounder  interest  is  a  twofold  relation  which  he  bears 
to  that  elemental  and  radical  antithesis.  On  the  one  hand,  he  is  the 
last  of  the  very  few  supremely  great  voices  through  whom  that  side 
of  the  antithesis  for  which  the  modern  world  thinks  it  has  no  place 

i  Supra,  p.  7  seq. 
115 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

has  found  express,  and  at  the  same  time  orginal,1  formulation  for 
itself.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  while  the  tendency  in  question  secures 
in  him  this  express  and  unmistakable  utterance  for  itself,  he  is  forced 
to  go  beyond  it,  and  so  in  his  system  it  is  seen  standing  face  to  face 
with  its  great  and  age-long  opponents. 

Such  is  the  historical  position  of  Spinoza.  Of  the  two  relations 
which  make  up  that  position — the  relation  to  the  Cartesian  philoso 
phy,  the  relation  to  Mysticism — the  one  mentioned  last  is  logically 
the  first,  in  the  sense  that  that  elemental  antithesis  is  deeper  than 
the  division  into  historical  periods  and  schools.  So  that,  in  seeking 
to  view  Spinoza  in  his  historical  position,  it  is  to  that  fundamental 
distinction  that  we  must  turn  first.  And  to  understand  it  as  it  appears 
in  Spinoza,  we  must  first  endeavour  to  understand  it  as  it  is  in  itself 
and  for  its  own  sake.  To  do  that,  we  must  consider  two  things :  first 
how  it  arises;  secondly,  its  chief  appearances  in  history. 


III. 

In  attempting  to  understand  how  that  distinction  arises  we  have 
to  consider,  first  what  the  fundamental  instinct  and  presupposition 
of  all  scientific  work  is,  secondly  the  two  ways  in  which  that  instinct 
may  fulfil  itself  when  science  reaches  its  final  or  metaphysical  stage. 
First,  then,  the  endeavour  of  any  particular  "  special  science  "  is  to 
find  unity  of  principle  in  the  phenomena  with  which  it  deals.  And 
the  endeavour  of  science  as  a  whole — or,  in  the  words  just  used,  the 
endeavour  of  science  in  its  metaphysical  stage — is  to  see  the  world 
as  one.  It  is  true  that  in  this,  its  last  and  highest  task,  science  some 
times  falls  by  the  way;  and  falls  with  so  decided  a  motion  that  it 
remains  fixed  where  it  has  fallen.  That  is  to  say,  certain  meta 
physicians  and  certain  schools  of  metaphysic,  regard  their  work  as 

i  Original,  not  as  standing  out  of  relation  to  earlier  men  of  thought— that  were  to  deny 
•what  has  just  been  affirmed— but  as  being  the  outcome  of  the  independent  working  of 
Spinoza's  own  mind  upon  the  material  furnished  to  it,  whether  by  previous  thinkers  or  by 
his  own  experience  of  life.  The  word  is  inserted  to  exclude  teachers  such  as  Schopenhauer, 
whose  formulation  of  this  same  tendency  can  scarcely  be  called  an  original  movement, 
but  is  rather  a  revival  of  an  ancient  system  and  a  delivering  over  of  the  Kantian  episte- 
mology  to  it  to  be  its  handmaid. 

116 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

completed  before  they  have  reached  a  One  at  all.  They  remain  to 
the  end  with  a  multitude  of  eternal  "  distinct  existences  "  on  their 
hands.  It  is  true,  too,  that  systems  formed  in  this  way — monad- 
ologies,  sensationalisms,  atomisms — have  taken  a  very  great  place 
in  the  history  of  philosophy.  And  still  farther,  they  have  been  very 
useful  there.  But  the  true  nature  of  that  usefulness  should  be  recog 
nised.  The  man  who  understands  that  the  search  of  science,  from 
its  lowest  stage  to  its  highest,  is  a  search  after  unity,  will  also 
understand  what  the  genuine  significance  is,  of  a  pluralistic  termina 
tion  of  the  scientific  endeavour;  namely,  that  the  science  which  so 
terminates  has  taken  as  a  highest  and  ultimate  category  some 
principle  which  is  not  powerful  enough  to  link  together  the  stubbornly 
diverse  factors  of  the  world.  That  is  to  say,  the  pluralistic  systems 
are  reductiones  ad  absurdum  of  the  methods  which  have  produced 
them.  And  it  is  for  this  very  reason  that  the  usefulness  of  these 
systems  in  the  history  of  philosophy  has  been  so  great.  They  have 
been  stages  on  the  way  to  insight.  At  certain  times  they  have  made 
clear — to  those  who  could  understand — the  inadequacy  and  inner 
hollowness  of  some  popular  school  or  of  some  trusted  method.  At 
other  times  they  have  deepened  the  problem  for  some  too  hasty 
monism,  setting  over  against  its  thesis  a  stubborn  and  resolute 
antithesis.  In  a  word,  they  have  been  steps,  worked  out  often  with 
great  keenness  and  acuteness,  in  that  long  dialectic  process  which  is 
the  history  of  philosophy. 

But,  as  already  has  been  noted,  the  very  nature  of  the  attempt  of 
science — the  very  nature  of  such  a  thing  as  a  search  after  law  in  the 
diversities  of  the  world — involves  that,  unless  that  scientific  attempt 
is  to  be  false  to  itself,  its  last  and  highest  view  of  the  world  must  be 
a  view  in  which  the  world  is  seen  as  one.  So  that,  granting  to  the 
full  the  usefulness  of  the  pluralistic  systems  in  the  dialectic  develop 
ment  of  philosophical  insight,  it  remains  that  in  them,  as  was  said 
above,  the  scientific  endeavour  is  seen  "  falling  by  the  way  and 
remaining  fixed  where  it  falls."  But  the  radical  and  elemental  dis 
tinction  which  we  are  now  concerned  to  understand,  is  a  distinction 
between  the  systems  of  philosophy  which,  with  all  their  errors,  have 
not  erred  in  that  fashion,  but  have  pushed  their  way  through  to  a 

117 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

unitary  view  of  the  world.  And  the  distinction  consists  precisely  in 
the  way  in  which  they  do  thus  push  their  way  through  to  a  One. 

For  both  sides  take  their  rise  in  a  profound  discontent — sometimes 
almost  purely  intellectual,  sometimes  moral  or  religious  as  well — with 
the  manifoldness,  the  changeableness,  the  dividedness,  the  imperfec 
tion  and  disorder,  of  our  everyday  experience.  But  the  one  side 
proceeds  from  the  unsatisfactory  Many  to  a  One  whose  distinctive 
character  is  simply  this — that  it  is  not  the  Many.  While  the  other 
side  proceeds  from  the  unsatisfactory  Many  to  a  One  which  is  the 
Many  over  again — but  the  Many  as  truly  or  adequately  known,  and 
in  the  light  of  that  adequate  interpretation  seen  to  be  no  longer 
unsatisfactory.  On  the  former  view,  manifoldness  and  dividedness 
are  inconsistent  with  the  One;  on  the  latter,  they  are  necessary  to  it. 
To  the  former,  the  infinite  excludes  finitude ;  to  the  latter,  it  mediates 
itself  through  finitude — is  an  infinity  of  determinations.  To  the 
former,  again,  the  eternal  is  no  home  of  change  and  of  time;  to  the 
latter,  it  is  at  once  the  home  and  the  law  and  the  informing  spirit  of 
time  and  of  the  changing  things  of  time.  To  the  former,  God  is  all 
in  all ;  the  world  can  be  only  a  shadow,  from  which  the  wise  man  will 
set  himself  free  in  order  that  in  God  he  may  become  at  one  with 
reality.  But  to  the  latter,  the  world  is  the  process  of  the  realisation  of 
divine  ends,  and  thus  is  in  organic  connexion  with  God  and  is  a  true 
field  of  labour  to  the  sons  of  God. 

Philosophy,  in  a  word,  is  the  apprehension  of  the  unity  and 
eternity  of  all  true  existence.  But  men  differ  in  the  way  in  which 
they  pass  from  the  diverse  and  changing  elements  of  their  daily 
experience  to  their  vision  of  that  unity.  To  some  it  is  a  One  which 
is  not  the  world,  and  in  whose  presence  the  world  fades  away.  To 
others  it  is  a  One  which  fulfils  itself  through  the  whole  system  of 
the  changes  and  diversities  of  the  world;  it  is  the  light  and  the  life 
of  men,  and  of  the  whole  universe  of  experience.  In  both  cases  the 
effort  of  man  is  to  see  truly;  and  to  see  truly  by  seeing  under  the 
form  of  eternity.  But  upon  the  one  view,  the  things  of  to-day  and 
to-morrow  cannot  endure  the  light  of  eternity;  they  vanish  as  dreams 
vanish,  when  the  soul  is  aroused  from  troubled  sleep  and  the  delusions 
of  the  night  fall  from  it  and  are  gone.  While  to  the  other  view  the 

118 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

things  and  interests  of  time  lose  indeed  their  fleeting  and  self-centred 
individuality;  but  only  to  be  seen  in  their  truth  as  elements  of 
eternity.  They  die,  but  in  dying  find  a  life  over  which  death  has  no 
power;  for  now  they  live  not  unto  themselves,  but  in  the  eternal  and 
unto  the  eternal.  To  this  type  of  philosophy,  the  particular  things 
and  interests  of  our  experience,  so  far  from  being  mere  appearances 
professing  a  reality  to  which  they  have  no  claim,  are  in  truth  more 
real  even  than  they  seem  to  be.  So  that  this  philosophy  is  a 
philosophy  humane  and  kindly.  It  is  hospitable  to  all  forms  of  being 
— though  it  has  its  sternness  in  insisting  that  each  shall  recognise 
its  place  and  devote  itself  to  its  own  function.  Every  lineament  in 
the  face  of  nature  is  dear  to  it;  but  its  special  delight  is  with  man 
and  his  history.  The  labour  of  man,  the  achievement  of  man,  the 
glory  and  the  tragedy  which  are  never  far  from  any  man's  heart — it 
is  never  weary  of  attempting  to  set  these  in  the  light  of  eternity  and 
to  show  them  transfigured  by  that  light.  But  the  philosophy  which 
stands  over  against  this  can  give  no  such  welcome  to  all  the  half- 
earthly  half-heavenly  content  of  our  life.  Not  that  it  does  not  love 
men.  In  its  greater  historical  forms  it  has  loved  men  with  the 
profoundest  and  most  passionate  of  all  the  forms  of  love — that  over 
whelmed  with  the  sense  of  tragedy ;  its  love  being  not  that  of  delight, 
but  that  of  a  great  pity  for  the  hapless  creature  whom  it  saw  losing 
himself  in  things  which,  not  being  Gpd,  are  nothing  and  worse  than 
nothing.  But  the  very  principle  which  gave  such  passion  to  its  love 
for  man  made  it  stand  aloof  from  man's  ordinary  life.  It  made  its 
home  neither  with  his  daily  affairs,  nor  with  the  humanities,  nor 
with  nature.  To  pass  from  its  great  opponent  to  it  is  as  if  one  passed 
from  Athens — from  the  thronged  harbours  of  the  Piraeus,  from  the 
voices  of  statesmen  and  sophists  and  tragedians,  from  the  gatherings 
of  men  who  delighted  in  life  and  in  one  another  and  in  the  exercise 
of  all  the  powers  that  their  natures  included — to  some  solemn  temple 
of  Lacedaemon,  standing  apart  in  grave  strength  and  austere  majesty, 
changeless  from  age  to  age,  while  in  hollow  Sparta  the  generations  of 
mortal  men  hastened  to  death. 

This,  then,  is  the  deepest  of  those  divisions  that  have  sundered 

119 


THE   METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

into  diverse  schools  and  tendencies  the  long  attempt  of  man  to  under 
stand  himself  and  his  world.  It  is  a  first  and  fundamental  distinction 
which  the  student  must  understand  if  he  is  to  understand  the  history 
of  philosophy  at  all.  That  history  seems  crowded  with  a  multitude  of 
structures;  and  the  difference  of  these  from  one  another  seems  as 
great  as  their  internal  complexity.  But  when  the  investigator  digs 
down  into  them,  what  he  comes  upon  at  last  is  one  or  other — more 
often  both — of  the  two  great  tendencies  now  before  us.  These  are 
elemental  in  character,  primitive,  simple;  and  they  are  of  immeasur 
able  antiquity ;  for  they  are  as  old  as  the  dissatisfaction  of  the  human 
soul  with  its  imperfect  being  and  with  its  momentary  and  transient 
experiences.  Their  opposition  has  moulded  the  whole  dialectical 
evolution  of  man's  endeavour  to  understand  his  life.  From  the 
beginnings  alike  of  religion  and  of  reflective  thought  they,  like  inner 
forces,  have  guided  the  main  currents;  and  have  determined  the 
proportions  of  the  greater  systems.  The  history  of  their  warfare— 
and  of  their  combinations  with  each  other — is,  on  its  practical  side, 
the  history  of  the  religious  life;  and,  on  its  theoretical  side,  the 
history  of  philosophy. 

So  long  as  we  understand  the  essential  movement  of  these  two 
tendencies,  it  matters  little  what  names  we  give  them.  Some  designa 
tions,  however,  we  must  have,  if  only  for  convenience  of  reference. 
The  broad  contrast  between  the  two,  as  tendencies  or  methods,  may 
be  indicated  by  the  terms  "  abstract "  and  "  concrete  " ;  or  by  the 
terms  "  analytic  "  and  "  synthetic  " ;  or  we  may  borrow  terms  from 
the  older  theologians,  and  call  the  one  the  via  negativa,  the  other  the 
via  affirmativa.  To  find  names  for  the  views  of  the  world  which  arise 
from  these  tendencies  is  on  the  one  side  fairly  easy,  on  the  other  some 
what  difficult.  The  philosophy  of  the  via  negativa — that  which  in 
moving  toward  the  One  denies  the  Many — may,  when  it  confines  itself 
to  pure  theory,  be  called  "  abstract  pantheism,"  or  from  another  point 
of  view  "  acosmism."1  But  when  it  goes  beyond  pure  theory,  and  is 

i  A  term  accurate  in  the  sense  of  giving  a  negative  name  to  a  negative  movement  of 
thought.  Yet  (leaving  aside  Hegel's  appropriate  use  of  it  in  replying  to  those  who  accused 
Spinoza  of  Atheism)  it  jars  upon  one  who  rememhers  how  exceedingly  positive  is  the 
impulse— the  impulse  after  reality— out  of  which  this  negative  movement  of  thought  has 
so  often  arisen. 

120 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

at  once  a  view  of  reality  and  a  way  of  life,  it  is  Mysticism — the  pan- 
theistische  My  stile  of  that  saying  of  Eothe  which  Dr.  Martineau  put 
upon  the  title-page  of  his  Spinoza, 

Der  pantheistischen  Mystik  ist  wirJclich  Gott  alles, 
Dem  gemeinen  Pantheismus  ist  alles  Gott. 

And  having  the  general  name  of  Mysticism,  we  need  scarcely,  for  our 
present  purpose,  concern  ourselves  with  names  for  its  various  types. 
For  while  it  is  true  that  the  points  of  departure  from  which  men  have 
proceeded  to  an  abstract  One  are  very    various,  yet  the    conclusion 
itself,  when  reached,  can  scarcely  be  said  to  have  diverse  forms.     To 
that  "  lion's  den  "  many  paths  may  lead — some  purely    theoretical, 
some  religious — but  to  all  of  them  it  is  a  lion's  den.    There  are  differ 
ent  kinds  of  Mysticism  only  in  the  sense  that  men  come  to  Mysticism 
along  different  ways,  under  different  impulses,  in  different  tempers. 
But  on  the    other  side  the    subdivisions  are    numerous  and  of  the 
utmost  importance.     For  here  the  Many  are  not  lost  in  the  One,  but 
preserved  in  the  One.     The    One    is    the    source    and    constitutive 
principle  of  the  world — the  principle  of  connexion  which  links  its 
many  factors  and  elements  together  into  one  orderly  system.     Hence, 
what  the  nature  of  that  connexion  is    (and  consequently  what  the 
nature  of  the  world,  and  what  the  nature  of  our  life  in  it)  depends  on 
the  nature  of  the  One.     And  that  nature  may  be  apprehended  upon 
many  different  intellectual  levels — i.e.,  by  many  different  categories. 
For  reflective  thought  began  with  simple  categories  which  could  not 
do  justice  to  the  positive  relation  between  the  details  of  the  world  and 
their  supreme  and  eternal  principle ;  and  from  these,  advanced  to  cate 
gories  more  concrete  and  therefore  at  once  more  comprehensive  and 
more  penetrating.    We  thus  get  an  ascending  series  of  views,  less  or  more 
adequate  according  as  the  category  employed  is  less  or  more  adequate 
to  that  which  is  to  be  apprehended.    It  may  be  broadly  stated  that  the 
lower  forms  of  these  are  dominated  by  the  idea  of  necessity  a  tergo — 
there  is  somehow  a  beginning,  or  cause,   or    substance,   and    from 
it  things  "  follow  "  or  "  flow  down,"  the  course  of  the  flow  being  abso 
lutely  determined  by  the  nature  of  the  cause  or  source ;  while  the  higher 
are    dominated    by  the    conception  of  spirit,   and    the    consequent 

121 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

conceptions  of  teleology,  and  of  a  rational  necessity  union  with  which 
is  true  freedom.  To  those  lower  forms — since  in  the  last  analysis  they 
must  regard  all  particular  things  as  the  modes  which  in  their  totality 
make  up  the  eternal  One — we  might  apply  Rothe's  term,  gemeiner 
Pantheismus;  or  we  might  use  some  such  name  as  "  naturalistic  Pan 
theism."  The  higher  forms  are  usually  denoted  by  the  name  Ideal 
ism,  in  its  greater  sense  as  defined  on  a  previous  page;1  though,  as 
there  noted,  even  in  Idealism  we  have  to  remember  the  distinction 
between  a  more  concrete  form  which  believes  that  the  eternal,  rational 
spirit  fulfils  its  purpose  through  the  whole  process  of  the  world,  and  a 
more  abstract  form  which  can  see  God  only  in  pure  reason,  and  is 
obliged,  therefore,  to  condemn  the  world  of  the  senses.2  With  these 
subdivisions,  however,  we  are  not  directly  concerned  at  this  point. 
What  we  must  do  here  is  to  fix  firmly  in  our  minds  the  original  and 
fundamental  distinction  itself  between  the  tendency  which  is  abstract 
and  negative,  and  that  which  is  affirmative  and  concrete. 

1  Supra,  p.  11.      Cf.  infra,  pp.  209,  210. 

2  To  the  student  of  "  Logik  "—the  science  whose  business  it  is  (or  was)  to  deal  with  the 
categories  and  hence  to  arrange  the  various  types  of  philosophy  in  the  order  of  their 
advance  from  abstractness   toward  concreteness— this  matter  of   classification  will  of 
course  offer  no  difficulties.    All  these  tendencies  and  types  can  be  arranged  as  stages  in  a 
single  process  of  logical  evolution.     The  first— the  thorough  carrying  out  of  the  via 
negativa—stand.s  at  the  beginning  where  the  categories  employed  are  altogether  abstract 
(the  categories  of  pure  Being).    The  third  stands  at  the  end,  where  a  highest  category  has 
been  gained  which  is  altogether  concrete  (Absolute  Idealism).      While    the   remaining 
forms  are  the  stages  which  constitute  the  long  road  between— one  of  the  most  striking  of 
these  being  that  which,  as  its  highest  category,  uses  the  conception  of  causation  (whether 
physical  or  logical)  in  such  a  way  as  to  give  us  a  view  of  the  universe  as  a  great  process  of 
necessity  a  tergo.    Those  intermediate  types  have  the  common  characteristic  that  they 
have  not  felt  the  pressure  of  the  problem  of  the  self ;  they  have  not  grasped  the  fact  that 
"  things  "  (extended  things  as  much  as  any  other)  are  objects  existing  for  and  through  a 
self  which  holds  together  many  "experiences"  in  the  unity  of  one  experience;  to  them, 
in  other  words,  man  is  simply  a  part  of  nature ;  whatever  principles  are  adopted  as 
explaining  the  things  which  seem  to  exist  in  their  own  right  in  space  and  time,  are  ipso 
facto  adopted  as  explaining  man.    And  it  is  when  the  pressure  of  the  problem  of  the  self 
(usually  in  a  special  form— the  problem  of  the  possibility  of  knowledge)  is  felt,  that 
philosophy  passes  upward  from  those  intermediate  types  to  the  Idealistic.    In  the  exam 
ination  of  human  experience  a  synthetic  principle,  self-conscious,  self-distinguishing, 
self-determining,  is  found ;  and  such  a  principle  furnishes  the  key  for  the  solution  of  the 
problem  how  the  many  facts  and  beings  of  the  world,  without  losing  their  particularity, 
can  be  linked  together  into  one  reality.    Self-distinguishing  and  self -determining  spirit- 
so  science  finds  at  the  end  of  its  long  ascent— is  the  principle  of  unity-in-diversity  which 
enables  us  to  view  the  universe  as  one,  without  abstracting  from,  or  condemning  as 
illusion,  that  manifoldness  of  existence  which  is  found,  not  only  in  the  multiplex  life  of 
nature,  but  also  in  the  divisions  of  the  intellectual  and  moral  and  religious  life  of  man. 

122 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

XD.  the  thought  of  Spinoza  both  these  tendencies  are  present.  The 
former — the  tendency  to  the  via  negativa — is  not  only  present  in  him, 
but  is  that  first  and  fundamental  thing  in  his  thinking  with  which 
the  student  must  begin  if  he  is*  at  all  to  understand  Spinoza  as  Spinoza 
actually  was.  But  in  that  large  and  sincere  and  open  mind,  the 
unquestioned  domination  of  the  negative  tendency  was  impossible.  To 
such  forms  of  the  other  tendency  as  could  enter  his  field  of  thought 
he  gave  fair  hearing,  and  dealt  as  he  was  able  with  the  problems  which 
these  forced  upon  him.  Of  this,  the  result  was  not  so  much  the 
renunciation  of  the  negative  tendency,  as  the  setting  of  the  other  beside 
it;  or  rather  the  setting  of  two  forms  of  the  other  beside  it.  For,  as 
we  shall  see,,  he  set  beside  it,  in  fully  articulated  form,  what  on  the 
classification  noted  a  moment  ago  would  be  called  a  lower  type  of  the 
positive  or  synthetic  view.  But  then  in  certain  connexions  he  was 
driven  even  beyond  that,  and  worked  out  doctrines  which  cannot 
indeed  be  called  a  system,  but  are  prophetic  hints  and  glimpses  calling 
for  the  highest  type  of  the  concrete  view,  i.e.,  for  Idealism.  In  order, 
then,  to  understand  him  as  he  was  and  to  follow  his  thinking  along 
the  line  of  its  own  journey,  we  shall  study  first  how  he  was  led  toward 
the  negative  or  mystic  conception  of  reality,  and  then  his  advance 
from  it  to  the  other  points  of  view  just  spoken  of.  But — as  was  noted 
a  moment  ago — to  study  intelligently  the  negative  tendency  as  it  is  in 
Spinoza,  it  will  be  wise  first  to  study  it  on  its  own  merits  and  for  its 
own  sake.  And  that  can  best  be  done  historically. 

IV. 

In  the  age-long  effort  of  man  to  find  out  what  he  is,  and  what  his 
experience  means,  and  what  the  true  way  of  life  for  him  is,  this 
abstract  or  negative  way  of  thinking  has  shown  itself  times  innumer 
able.  In  some  cases  it  has  played  the  part  of  a  Nemesis  of  thought, 
appearing  unbidden  in  the  systems  of  those  who  face  with  inadequate 
categories  the  ultimate  problem  of  science.1  But  these  cases  need  not 
be  dwelt  upon  here.  For,  in  the  history  of  man,  it  has  had  a  greater 

1  A  remarkable  instance  is  the  case  of  the  development  from  Sir  William  Hamilton 
through  Dean  Mansel  to  Mr.  Spencer. 

123 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

part  than  that  to  play.  Strange  as  the  fact  may  seem,  this  austere 
and  abstract  tendency,  which  has  for  its  goal  a  formless  Absolute  and 
an  eternity  devoid  of  time,  has  not  only  dominated  the  thought,  but 
has  governed  the  life,  of  whole  races  and  nations.  Stranger  still,  it 
has  at  times  regenerated  religion,  and  broken  up  spiritual  stagnation. 
It  has  even  helped  to  shatter  political  tyrannies.  And  as  one  might 
conjecture  beforehand,  a  tendency  that  has  taken  so  great  a  place  in 
the  life  of  man  has  not  wanted  for  expression  in  the  works  of  the  great 
masters  of  systematic  thought.  Sometimes  it  has  ruled  half  the 
divided  heart  of  a  supreme  teacher.  Sometimes,  on  the  other  hand, 
from  a  method  or  a  point  of  departure  in  which  it  lay  latent,  it  has 
worked  its  way,  with  a  logic  as  inevitable  as  the  decrees  of  fate,  to  its 
full  meaning ;  and  then  has  shown  itself  as  the  fundamental  and  con 
trolling  factor  in  the  thought  of  some  great  man,  or  some  great  school, 
or  some  remarkable  age. 

The  cases  of  the  former  kind  are  of  the  very  deepest  interest. 
They  stand  central  in  the  historical  development  of  philosophy;  one 
might  almost  call  them  its  great  ganglia.  Here,  however,  it  is  possible 
to  refer  only  to  two  of  these.  The  first  is  the  greater.  In  the  thought 
of  Plato  the  negative  tendency  is  present,  confronting  the  affirmative ; 
and  there,  in  the  presence  of  its  opponent,  it  takes  on,  more  than  ever 
before  in  the  history  of  man  and  more  than  ever  after,  the  characters 
which  are  native  to  it — the  solemnity,  the  unearthly  splendour,  the 
austere  Lacedaemonian  grace,  appropriate  to  the  vision  of  an  eternal 
being  in  whose  presence  the  weaker  things  of  time  pass  away  and  are 
not.  But  while  it  is  present,  and  knows  itself,  it  cannot  prevail.  For 
in  Plato,  as  in  all  the  great  cases  of  its  occurrence,  the  negative  tend 
ency  takes  its  rise  in  that  which  is  the  genuine  beginning  and  the 
genuine  inspiration  of  all  science,  and  of  all  philosophy,  and  in  one 
sense  of  all  religion;  namely,  in  the  instinctive  search  of  the  spirit 
which  is  man  for  the  abiding  and  the  unchangeable ;  in  the  passion  for 
the  eternal.  But  of  the  men  who  are  thus  animated  by  the  passion  for 
the  eternal — the  men  who,  as  we  are  wont  to  say,  are  "not  of  this 
world  "•  —there  are  two  classes.  Some  who  are  "  not  of  this  world  " 
are  so  in  the  literal  sense.  So  far  as  they  can,  they  walk  without 
transgression  in  the  way  of  the  negative  theology.  Their  journey 

124 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

toward  their  home  in  God,  is  a  journey  away  from  this  world.  But 
others,  who  are  "  not  of  this  world,"  are  for  that  very  reason  all  the 
more  truly  citizens  of  this  world.  Their  knowledge  that  their 
dwelling-place  is  in  the  eternal  makes  all  the  profounder  and  all  the 
more  genuine  their  citizenship  in  that  temporal  order  which  is  "  a 
moving  image  of  eternity."1  And  as  between  these  alternatives 
Plato's  position  was  peculiar.  A  certain  Dorian  quality  of  soul 
struggled  in  him  with  an  Ionian  intellect  and  with  Athenian  training 
and  tastes  and  interests.  And  the  practical  tragedy  in  his  life2  partly 
withdrew  him  from  the  world,  partly  made  him  all  the  more  passion 
ately  earnest  about  the  reformation  of  the  world  within  the  forms  of 
its  present  order.  The  negative  tendency  lay  very  close  at  his  heart; 
yet,  upon  the  whole,  it  is  the  other  that  prevails  in  his  philosophy. 
The  Ideas  remain  determinate  forms — and  determinate  rational  forms. 
The  One  (i.e.,  the  Idea  of  Good)  does  not  by  its  presence  condemn  to 
unreality  the  lower  Ideas  in  their  individual  distinctness;  nor  for  the 
apprehension  of  it  is  a  type  of  consciousness  above  the  rational 
required.  And  even  more  than  that  can  be  said.  Of  the  two  inter 
pretations  of  Plato,  that  which  sees  the  Ideas  as  in  organic  union  with 
man's  present  world  and  present  experience,  is  really  more  true  to 
Plato  than  that  which  sees  the  Ideas  as  dwelling  altogether  apart  from 
the  world.  What  Mysticism  does  for  Plato  is,  not  to  overcome  him, 
but  rather  to  give  loftiness  of  soul,  and  a  certain  undernote  of  tragedy, 
to  his  Idealism.  Indeed  his  thought  as  a  whole  is  an  example  of  the 
fact  that  a  great  and  complex  process  often  takes  on  a  wider  move 
ment,  a  new  and  higher  order  of  power,  when  a  negative  element 
enters  among  its  constituents. 

The  other  case  lies  close  to  ourselves.  A  negative  movement  of 
thought  is  present  in  the  very  system  in  which  the  metaphysic  of  the 
present  day  recognises  its  proximate  fountain-head — in  the  critical 
philosophy  of  Immanuel  Kant.  But,  although  more  than  twenty 
centuries  had  intervened — some  of  them  filled  with  hard  thinking, 
others  given  to  eager  conquest  of  the  world — yet  the  negative  tendency 
is  in  Kant  far  less  aware  than  in  Plato  of  its  own  true  nature. 

i  Timaeus,  37  DE.  2  See  pp.  222,  223,  infra. 

125 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

Appearing  first  as  a  gulf  between  the  categories  and  the  materials  given 
in  sense — and  then  going  on  through  other  dualisms  to  that  final  one 
between  the  phenomena  given  to  the  understanding,  and  the  real  world 
which  is  the  field  of  the  rational  will — it  operates  mainly  as  a  potent 
source  of  difficulty  and  confusion ;  and  the  first  labour  of  the  followers 
of  Kant  was  to  overcome  it,  so  that  Kant's  synthetic  view  might  be 
developed  to  its  full  significance. 

It  is  hard  to  turn  away  from  a  more  detailed  study  of  these  two 
cases.  But  they  do  not  give  us  exactly  what  we  want  here  at  the 
beginning.  What  we  need  here  is  to  see  the  negative  tendency,  as  far 
as  possible,  in  the  purity  of  its  type ;  to  see  it  as  it  is  in  itself.  What 
we  must  do  is  to  turn  to  the  other  great  class  of  its  appearances — those 
in  which,  from  the  method  or  the  point  of  departure  wherein  it  is 
latent,  it  advances  with  uninterrupted  logic,  moving  with  its  own 
motion,  working  out  its  own  dialectic,  until,  as  one  may  say,  it 
possesses  the  whole  field. 

Of  such  cases  there  are  three  in  particular,  which  (specially  when 
compared  with  one  another)  show  what  this  tendency  is;  show  what 
that  meaning  is,  which  it  has  in  it  at  its  beginning  and  develops  in  its 
course.  One  of  these  is  found  in  Greek  thought  before  the  problem  of 
the  self  had  come  clearly  to  view.  Here  the  tendency  shows  itself  in  a 
strictly  theoretical  form.  It  gives,  as  one  may  say,  a  sketch  of  itself 
in  its  purely  logical  outline.  But  it  did  not — in  that  land  and  at  that 
age,  it  could  not — enter  upon  the  full  work  of  a  philosophy.  It  neither 
became  a  guide  of  life,  nor  faced  the  full  weight  and  power  of  its  own 
theoretical  shortcoming.  The  second  is*  much  earlier  in  date ;  but 
much  fuller  in  articulation.  Among  the  Hindus  the  negative  tendency 
not  only  works  itself  out  with  a  singular  completeness  of  logical 
development,  but  also  undertakes  what  has  just  been  called  "  the  full 
work  of  a  philosophy."  It  puts  its  shoulder  to  the  wheel.  It  acts  as 
a  guide  of  life,  and  builds  up  an  ethic  and  a  philosophy  of  religion. 
While  in  the  third  case — the  Neo-Platonic — it  is  seen  at  last  recognis 
ing  its  great  theoretical  difficulty,  and  erecting,  in  the  effort  to  over 
come  that  difficulty,  a  structure  of  almost  monstrous  vastness. — And.  as 
we  shall  see,  there  is  a  fourth  case,  which  scarcely  adds  any  new  logical 
factor,  but  which  so  well  sums  up  in  itself  the  main  features  of  the 

126 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

three  cases  just  mentioned,  that  it  will  be  worth  our  while  to  take 
note  of  it  as  we  pass  from  these  historical  references  to  the  direct 
study  of  Spinoza. 

(a) 

What  we  are  to  see  in  the  Greek  case  is  the  pure  science,  the  pure 
logic,  of  the  matter,  given  in  a  very  brief  and  elementary  form,  but 
with  perfect  clearness.  This  case  we  shall  best  understand  by  consider 
ing  the  logical  position  in  which  men  inevitably  found  themselves  when 
they  first  attempted  to  be  scientific  in  their  thinking  about  the  world. 
First,  the  instinct  after  unity,  the  sense  of  the  oneness  of  all  existence, 
is  present ;  present  at  the  very  beginning,  for  without  it  there  could  be 
no  such  beginning.  It  may  be  unrecognised  and  unrefiected  upon ;  but 
without  its  implicit  operation  there  would  be  no  such  thing  as  the 
search  after  scientific  explanation  at  all.  The  mind  would  simply  rest 
each  instant  in  the  particulars  of  that  instant.  But,  ,  secondly,  the 
category  that  can  affect  the  unification  of  this  most  complex  world, 
must  be  a  very  complex  and  difficult  category.  But  such  a  category  is 
not  present  at  the  beginning.  Or  rather,  it  is  present  only  potentially 
and  shows  itself  only  in  flashes  of  prophetic  intuition.  As  a  clear 
instrument  of  the  reason,  employed  in  building  up  systematic  and 
assured  science,  it  is  gained  only  as  the  result  of  a  long  dialectic  labour 
in  which  category  after  category  is  entered  upon,  used  to  the  utmost  of 
its  power,  and  finally  taken  up  into  a  higher : — until  at  last  a  category 
is  reached  by  which  the  Many  are  shown  as  a  One,  with  no  rebels 
remaining  outside  to  prove,  by  the  very  fact  of  their  rebellion,  the 
inadequacy  of  the  category  for  its  work  of  unification. 

So  then,  at  the  beginning  the  demand  for  unity  is  present.  But 
the  category  by  which  the  Many  can  be  seen  as  One,  is,  in  the  sense  just 
mentioned,  not  present.  What  almost  inevitably  results  is  a  stage  of 
.thinking  in  which  the  One  runs  away  with  the  Many — or  to  speak  more 
decorously,  in  which  the  Many  are  lost  in  the  One.  This  whelming  of 
the  Many  in  the  One  is  likely,  indeed,  to  take  place  near  the  beginning 
rather  than  at  the  beginning.  Near  the  beginning;  for  there  the 
categories  are  simple,  abstract,  inadequate.  But  not  precisely  at  the 
beginning.  For  the  denial  of  the  manifold  involves  two  things  which 

127 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

at  the  very  beginning  can  scarcely  be  present;  first,  as  we  shall  see 
presently,  an  unflinching,  uninterrupted  consistency  in  carrying  a 
given  category  to  its  extreme  and  absolute  application;  and  secondly, 
a  high  degree  of  speculative  courage.  But  as  soon  as  the  scientific 
intellect  has  taken  on  some  considerable  impetus  and  has  come  to 
feel  tolerably  sure  of  itself,  then  we  may  look  for  such  an  affirmation 
of  the  unity  of  being  as  makes  its  manif  oldness  a  mere  illusion. 

Among  the  Greeks — in  whose  early  men  of  thought  the  pure 
intellect,  serene  and  undistracted,  enslaved  neither  by  force  from 
without  nor  by  superstitious  fears  within,  stood  free  to  work  its  way 
without  interruption  through  the  dialectic  of  its  categories — this 
tendency  came  to  the  forefront  just  in  the  place  indicated.  The  name 
connected  with  its  clear  and  full  emergence  is  the  great  name  of 
Parmenides. 

If  we  consider  the  exact  situation  which  Parmenides  faced,  we 
shall  see  both  how  clear  his  logic  was,  and  how  absolutely  inevitable 
wa*  the  conclusion  to  which  he  came.  He  stood  face  to  face  with  the 
particular  things  of  the  world,  and  these  were  not  self-intelligible. 
Of  this  plant,  this  cloud,  this  cliff  that  the  sea  is  wearing  down,  one 
has  to  say,  "  It  is."  But  there  was  a  time,  and  there  will  again  be  a 
time,  when  one,  if  present,  would  have  to  say,  "  It  is  not."  But 
there  is  no  rest  for  the  intellect  in  such  things.  They  do  not  stand 
upon  their  own  feet.  They  are  and  they  are  not.  What  is  wanted  is 
something  which  will  supply  a  footing  to  these  things,  and  which  at 
the  same  time  will  itself  have  at  least  two  characters.  First,  it  must 
be  something  of  which  you  can  in  the  fullest  sense  of  the  words  say 
that  it  is : — at  no  time,  in  no  place,  under  no  circumstances,  must  you 
be  able  to  say  that  it  is  not.  Secondly,  it  must  be  something  which  is 
one  with  itself.  That  is,  it  must  always  remain  itself  throughout  all 
its  work  of  making  possible  these  particular  and  transient  "  things  " 
and  this  changing  order  of  "nature."  If,  for  instance,  it  be  some 
thing  which  condenses  itself  into  these  stones  and  rarifies  itself  into 
that  vapour,  it  must  still  remain  itself  throughout  all  those  trans 
formations.  And  this  second  character  follows  directly  from  the 
first;  the  "It  remains  itself,"  from  the  absolute  "It  is." 

The  first  Greek  men  of  science  faced  this  problem  as  well  as  they 

128 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

could.     They  used  such  intellectual  instruments,  such  categories,  as 
they  had.    And  the  category  which  they  had  was  the  first  and  simplest 
of  all  our  categories — that  of  Being.     This  category  they  used  in 
specific  and  very  naive  forms.    But  its  essential  character  was  always 
the  same : — Being  is  that  of  which  you  can  simply  affirm  that  it  is. 
Soon,  however,  these  men  of  science  found  themselves  in  difficulties 
of  a  most  serious  character.     Their  category  turned  a  very  unkindly 
and  very  uncompromising  face  toward  the  actual  existences  of  the 
world.    They  were — if  the  illustration  be  not  too  profane — somewhat 
in  the  position  of  a  man  who  has  discovered  that  space  is  two-dimen 
sional.    If  you  have  found  that  space  has  but  two  dimensions — that  all 
spatial  reality  exists  in  a  plane — you  must  leave  off  tying  sailors'  knots 
and  must  have  nothing  more  to  do  with  the  various  gymnastic  feats 
which  involve  motion  in  the  third  dimension.    And  if  you  find  your 
self  still  doing  these  things  you  must  declare  that  really  you  do  not  do 
them;  that  in  truth  they  are  but  illusions.    For  any  motion  is  either 
in  that  plane,  or  out  of  it ;  and  if  it  is  out  of  it,  it  is  unreal.    Just  so 
it  turned  out  to  be  with  the  category  of  Being.    These  things  of  time 
and  of  sense  are  continually  changing,  continually  swaying  back  and 
forth  between  "  is  "  and  "  is  not."    But  Being  is.    In  it  there  is  no 
"  is  not."    In  a  word,  there  is  no  place  in  it  for  change  and  for  things 
that  are  subject  to  change.    And  if  you  try  to  escape  the  difficulty  by 
making  the  conception  of  Being  into  the  conception  of  Substance;  if 
you  try  to  keep  both  the  Being  and  the  things,  by  viewing  the  Being 
as  the  substrate  of  the  things:  you  help  yourself  not  one  whit.     The 
old  difficulty  simply  recurs.     Here  is  this  particular  thing.     It  either 
has  Being  or  else  it  has  not  Being.     If  it  has  Being,  then  it  cannot 
have  any  sort  of  "  is  not "  about  it — for  how  can  "  is  not "  get  into 
the  pure  and  absolute  "  is  "  ?   That  is  to  say,  it  cannot,  among  other 
things,  have  any  change  in  it.     But  it  changes  even  while  we  are 
speaking  about  it.     Therefore  it  has  not  Being.    It  is  nothing  at  all. 
If  you  appeal  to  your  sense-experience,  your  sense-experience  must  be 
declared  to  be  at  once  an  absurdity  and  an  illusion.    Nor  can  you  be 
permitted  to  attempt  an  escape  by  setting  up  a  distinction  in  the  thing 
between   Substance    and  Accidents.      For    precisely    the   same    test 
banishes  the  Accidents  into  nothingness. 

10  129 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

So  that  when  .these  early  men  of  science  attempt  to  understand 
the  world  by  means  of  the  only  categories  they  have  securely  grasped 
— those  of  Being  or  of  Substance — the  solution,  as  soon  as  its  logic  is 
worked  out,  swallows  up  the  original  problem.  On  the  level  of  those 
categories,  the  assertion  that  Keality  is,  involves  the  assertion  that  it 
is  One,  and  that  the  Many  and  the  Finite  and  the  Changeable  are  not. 

The  foregoing  is  simply  the  argument  of  Parmenides  stated  in 
general  terms;1  and  of  course  with  this  difference  that  Parmenides 
neither  had,  nor  could  be  expected  to  have,  any  suspicion  of  the 
possible  inadequacy  of  his  categories.  He  used  his  categories  in  all 
good  faith.  He  saw  that  from  their  point  of  view  the  disjunction  of 
being  and  non-being,  of  "  is  "  and  "  is  not,"  is  absolute.  He  saw  that 
this  again  involved  that  reality  is  One,  and  its  apparent  manifoldness 
an  illusion.  And  this  he  stated  in  a  way  which  is  not  merely  clear 
and  convincing,  but  is  absolutely  final : 

.  .  .  "  One  path  only  is  left  for  us  to  speak  of,  namely, 
that  It  is.  In  it  are  very  many  tokens  that  what  is,  is  uncreated  and 
indestructible,  alone,  complete,  immovable,  and  without  end.  Nor 
was  it  ever,  nor  will  it  be ;  for  now  it  is,  all  at  once,  a  continuous  one. 
For  what  kind  of  origin  for  it  will  you  look  for?  In  what  way  and 
from  what  source  could  it  have  drawn  its  increase?  I  shall  not  let 
thee  say  nor  think  that  it  came  from  what  is  not ;  for  it  can  neither  be 
thought  nor  uttered  that  what  is  not  is.  And  if  it  came  from  nothing 
what  need  could  have  made  it  arise  later  -rather  than  sooner  ?  There 
fore  must  it  either  be  altogether  or  be  not  at  all.  Nor  will  the  force  of 
truth  suffer  aught  to  arise  besides  itself  from  that  which  in  any  way  is. 
Wherefore,  Justice  does  not  loose  her  fetters  and  let  anything  come 
into  being  or  pass  away,  but  holds  it  fast.  .  .  .  How  then 
can  what  is  be  going  to  be  in  the  future  ?  Or  how  could  it  come  into 
being?  If  it  came  into  being,  it  is  not;  nor  is  it  if  it  is  going  to  be 
in  the  future.  Thus  is  becoming  extinguished  and  passing  away 
not  to  be  heard  of.  ...  Nor  is  it  divisible.  .  .  .  More 
over  it  is  immovable.  .  .  .  without  beginning  and  without  end; 
since  coming  into  being  and  passing  away  have  been  driven  afar  off, 
and  true  belief  has  cast  them  away.  It  is  the  same,  and  it  rests  in  the 

i  "  In  general  terms  "—for  Parmenides  envisaged  reality  spatially.    Cf.  p.  131,  note. 

130 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

self-same  place,  abiding  in  itself.  .  .  .  And  there  is  not,  and 
never  shall  be,  any  time  other  than  that  which  is  present,  since  fate 
has  chained  it  so  as  to  be  whole  and  immovable.  Wherefore  all  these 
things  are  but  the  names  which  mortals  have  given,  believing  them  to 
be  true — coming  into  being  and  passing  away,  being  and  not  being, 
change  of  place  and  alteration  of  bright  colour."1 

"Being  is  One  and  is  self-identical;  the  many  are  not."  So 
stands  the  conclusion  of  Parmenides.  But  the  important  point  for 
our  purpose  is  to  note  how  absolutely  logical,  how  absolutely  consist 
ent  and  consequent,  is  the  argument  by  which  he  reaches  this  conclu 
sion.  He  stood  within  the  science  of  his  day  and  accepted  its 
procedure.  But  he  saw  with  thorough  clearness  what  the  ultimate 
meaning  of  that  procedure  was.  And  this  he  stated  in  a  form 
impressive,  complete,  valid  for  ever.2  Little  was  left  for  his  younger 
followers  to  do,  save  to  round  out  the  system  on  its  polemic  side  by 
showing  into  what  absurd  positions  men  get  themselves  when  they 
hold  to  the  reality  of  the  Many,  and  to  the  truthfulness  of  the  senses. 

Early  in  the  course  of  Greek  thought,  then,  the  negative  tendency 
stated  itself  with  intellectual  completeness  and  finality.  And  yet  it 
did  not  do  among  the  Greeks  the  full  work  of  a  philosophy.  It  did 
not  enter  upon  the  guidance  of  life.  From  the  day  of  Parmenides 
onward  one  does  not  find  the  most  earnest  men  among  the  Greeks 
being  led  by  it  to  have  done  with  the  illusion  of  the  Many,  and  to 
seek  the  true  fulfilment  of  their  being  in  a  changeless  and  ineffable 
One.  And  the  reason  is  plain.  It  consists  partly  in  the  fact  that  this 
philosophy,  as  a  philosophy,  was  outgrown  at  last  by  the  bringing 
forward  of  more  adequate  categories;  and  partly  in  the  character  of 

1  Burnet,  Early  Greek  Philosophy  (1892),  pp.  185-187. 

2  The  statement  in   the   text   deals   with  the  abiding  significance   of   Parmenides' 
argument,  as  a  purely  intellectual  form  of   the  logic  of  Mysticism.     Of  course,  with 
Parmenides,  as  with  most  men  who  stand  early  in  great  histories,  we  must  distinguish 
between  the  atmosphere  in  which  an  argument  moves,  and  the  essential  significance  of 
the  argument  which  moves  in  that  atmosphere.    The  atmosphere  in  which  Parmenides' 
argument  moved,  was  one  of  naive  Realism ;  he  envisaged  his  One  as  a  corporeal  sphere  ; 
and  in  doing  so,  did  not  quite  carry  out  his  own  principle  (v.  Burnet,pp.  342,  343,  §  141).  But 
his  argument  itself,  in  its  use  of  categories,  in  its  movement  from  conception  to  conception, 
goes  beyond  all  naive  Realism ;  goes  beyond  all  Realism  of  any  sort,  and  leads  straight 
toward  Mysticism. 

131 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

Greek  life.  In  the  life  of  the  Hellenes,  perfection  of  body  and  power 
of  soul  answered  to  fulness  of  opportunity.  They  lived  under  the 
clearest  of  skies.  They  were  served  generously  by  their  land  and  by 
their  sea.  They  had,  among  their  inherited  treasures,  the  "greatest 
births  of  time  "  in  literature  and  in  art,  and  they  were  engaged  almost 
daily  in  placing  beside  these,  companion-pieces  that  were  worthy  of 
them.  Life  they  knew  and  the  joy  of  life,  and  over  its  resources 
exercised  a  supreme  and  easy  mastery.  Nor  did  they  esteem  their 
life  the  less,  that  the  Mede  and  the  Canaanite  had  appeared  among 
them,  and  Marathon  and  Salamis  and  Himera  had  become  names 
for  ever.  Such  a  race,  living  such  a  life,  was  not  likely,  till  its  greater 
day  was  done,  to  furnish  apt  pupils  for  the  lesson  that  the  thronging 
interests  of  life  are  vanity  and  illusion,  and  that  wisdom  lies  in  with 
drawing  from  them  and  seeking  rest  in  a  reality  which  knows  neither 
change  nor  manifold. 

But  there  was  a  race  whose  life  had  come  to  be  burdened  by  the 
weight  of  an  immeasurable  and  hopeless,  pain.  And  there  the  thinking 
that  walks  in  the  via  negativa  entered  upon  the  full  function  of  a 
philosophy.  It  gave  to  the  generations  of  a  great  race  their  theoretical 
view  of  reality;  it  shaped — and  it  shapes — their  morality  and  their 
religion.  Hegel,  thinking  of  the  spirits  of  the  nations  as  existent  and 
particular  individuals,  tells  us  that  they  stand  around  the  throne  of 
the  universal  spirit,  the  spirit  of  the  world,  as  perfecters  of  its 
actuality  and  witnesses  and  ornaments  of  its  splendour.1  Each  race, 
like  an  attendant  spirit,  fulfils  by  its  intellectual  and  by  its  moral 
labours,  its  part  in  the  one  work  of  world-history.  In  this  great 
division  and  delegation  of  the  tasks  of  world-history,  it  would  almost 
seem  as  if  the  one  specially  committed  to  the  Hindu  race  was  the  full 
development  through  all  its  stages — was  the  full  articulation  both  as 
an  intellectual  and  as  a  moral  system — of  the  philosophy  of  the 
negative  way.  The  steps  in  that  long  labour  of  thought  by  which  this 
was  accomplished  we  have  now  to  trace. 

i  Philosophy  of  Eight,  §  352 ;  cf.  §  340. 


132 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

(ft) 

The  first  step  takes  us  back  to  the  very  fountain-head  of  the 
science  of  the  Aryan  peoples.  The  Vedic  poet  stands  where  all  orderly 
human  science  stood  at  its  beginning.  He  stands  face  to  face  with 
the  facts  and  forces  of  nature — with  sky  and  sun,  storm-wind  and 
dawn;  and  he  feels  that  these,  as  he  finds  them,  are  not  self -intelli 
gible  ;  he  feels  that,  as  they  stand,  they  do  not  exist  in  their  own  right. 
And  the  first  step  which  he  takes  in  healing  this  unsatisfactoriness  of 
the  facts  present  to  him,  is  one  in  which  the  scientific  instinct  and  the 
religious  instinct  go  hand  in  hand.  He  personifies  those  facts  and 
gives  to  them,  as  thus  personified,  the  attributes  of  deity. 

But  in  connexion  with  this,  the  Yedic  poets  did  one  of  the  most 
remarkable  things  in  human  history.  What  this  was,  can  best 
be  shown  by  contrasting  the  two  great  lines  of  thought  that  took  their 
rise  from  the  original  homeland  of  the  Aryans — the  Greek  and  the 
Vedic.  The  Greeks  very  early  separated  their  gods  from  the  natural 
phenomena  of  which  they  were  personifications,  and  humanised  them 
— gave  to  them  abiding  individualities,  clear,  definite,  characteristic, 
personal.1  While  this  remains  the  case,  the  gods,  whatever  they  may 
be  to  the  religious  consciousness,  are  of  little  value  to  the  scientific  or 
philosophic  consciousness — the  consciousness  which  seeks  to  make 
the  world  intelligible  and  needs  principles  of  explanation  for  doing 
so.  If  indeed  an  advance  toward  unity  were  to  be  made,  by  making 
some  god  supreme — whether  Zeus  or  'AvdyKij  or  Erinys — then  there 
would  be  at  least  a  possibility  of  the  scientific  consciousness  finding 
the  principle  of  unity  that  it  needs.  But  such  an  advance  the  early 
Greeks  can  scarcely  be  said  to  have  made.  The  consequence  was  that 
the  scientific  consciousness  had  to  wait  for  long  ages,  and  finally, 
with  the  Ionic  physicists,  to  make  an  altogether  new  beginning  on  its 
own  account. 

But  when  we  turn  back  to  the  Vedic  line,  we  find  something  quite 
different.  It  has  been  pointed  out  times  innumerable  that  in  the  Vedic 
hymns  whatsoever  deity  the  poet  addresses  is  viewed  for  the  time 
being  as  God,  supreme,  unlimited,  absolute ;  and  this  even  when  other 

i  E.  Caird,  Evolution  of  Religion  (1893),  vol.  I.,  p.  264  seg. 
133 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

deities  are  being  at  the  same  time  mentioned  by  name.  Varuna,  for 
instance,  is  addressed  as  Lord  of  all,  Lord  of  heaven  and  earth, 
upholding  the  whole  order  of  nature,  and  guardian  too  of  the  moral 
order  of  the  world.  The  breaking  of  his  laws  is  sin.  The  penitent 
sinner  is  to  pray  for  mercy  to  him.  But  presently  Indra  or  Agni  is 
addressed  in  the  same  way. 

This  fact  is  one  of  the  commonplaces  of  present-day  knowledge. 
But  what  has  not  always  been  made  so  clear  is  the  mental  condition 
out  of  which  it  arises.  What  it  means  is  this :  the  Vedic  poet,  how 
ever  religious  he  may  be,  has  never  ceased  to  have  that  in  him  which 
is  nothing  other  than  the  genuine  spirit  of  philosophy,  nothing  other 
than  the  genuine  movement  of  the  scientific  consciousness.  He  feels, 
no  matter  how  dimly,  the  oneness  of  nature.  Some  one  principle,  he 
feels,  some  one  power,  is  expressing  itself  through  all  this  variety  of 
wonderful  and  appalling  phenomena.  But  the  only  forms  which  he 
had  at  his  command  for  purposes  of  scientific  expression,  were  those 
forms  which  he  had  struck  out  for  himself  by  personifying  those  very 
phenomena — Indra  and  Agni  and  Varuna,  Ushas  and  the  Maruts, 
and  the  rest  of  Yagwavalkya's  "  three  and  three  hundred,  three  and 
three  thousand  "  gods.1  But  then  comes  the  trouble  that  no  one  of  all 
these  forms  is  adequate  to  the  expression  of  the  principle  or  power 
which  the  Vedic  thinker,  dimly  enough  at  first,  but  with  a  demand 
that  grows  continually  clearer,  is  groping  after.  No  one  of  them — for 
it  expresses  itself  in  them  all;  of  all  of  them  it  is  the  source.  And 
so  ihe  first  expedient  is  to  use  all  those  forms,  now  one,  now  another. 
A  sage,  Yaska  by  name,  who  lived  many  centuries  later,  puts  the  logic 
of  the  case  into  a  sentence — It  is  owing  to  the  greatness  of  the  deity 
that  the  Divine  Self  is  celebrated  as  if  it  were  many.2 

But  such  a  procedure  has  an  almost  inevitable  logical  outcome. 
As  time  goes  by  and  reflective  thought  comes  forward,  while  poetic 
intuition  and  poetic  nature-worship  recede,  two  things  come  into  ever 

1  "How  many  gods  are  there?"  asks  Vidagdha  Sakalya  of  Yaflwavalkya.    The  first 
answer  is  "three  and  three  hundred,  three  and  three  thousand."    But  this  number  is 
steadily  reduced— to  thirty-three— to  one  and  a  half— finally  to  one.    This  one  is  Brahman 
and  his  name  is  "  That. "— Brth.  Upanishad,  III.  9.  1-9.    (Sacred '-Books  of  the  East,  vol. 
XV.,  pp.  139-142.) 

2  Max  Miiller,   Three  Lectures  on  the  Veddnta  Philosophy,  (London,  1894),  p.  27.— 
Yaska  lived  circa  500  B.C. 

134 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

clearer  consciousness.  First,  that  what  is  really  being  sought  for  is 
One.  Secondly,  that  this  One  is  not  to  be  identified  with  any  of  the 
forms  just  referred  to — not  with  Varuna  the  Heaven,  nor  with  Indra 
the  giver  of  rain,  nor  with  Agni  the  fire,  nor  with  the  appalling 
Maruts,  the  storm-winds.  The  oneness  will  be  ever  more  strongly  and 
clearly  insisted  upon.  But  to  any  definite  determination  or  qualifica 
tion  of  it,  the  answer  will  come  to  be — and  did  come  to  be — "  Neti, 
neti."1  In  a  word,  the  goal  that  lay  straight  ahead  was  an  abstract 
One  and  an  illusory  manifold.  And  to  this  goal  the  thinkers  of  India 
advanced  with  a  logic  that  neither  flinched  nor  failed.  "  Sir,  tell  me 
Brahman,"  said  Vashkalin.  Thereupon  Bahva  became  quite  still. 
When  Vashkalin  had  asked  a  second  and  a  third  time,  Bahva  replied : 
"I  am  teaching  you  indeed,  but  you  do  not  understand.  Silent  is 
that  Self."2 

Such  was  the  first  great  step  taken  by  the  thought  of  India.  Its 
inner  movement  is  not  greatly  different  from  that  which  we  met  with 
in  the  case  of  Parmenides.  Its  search  after  the  One  moves  in  the 
logical  region  of  the  category  of  Being.  And  it  does  what  on  the  level 
of  that  category  is  inevitable.  It  absolutely  disjoins  "  is  "  and  "  is 
not."3  And  it  is  thereupon  obliged  to  exclude  from  reality  the  deter 
minations  which  involve  an  element  of  "  is  not."  But  the  next  great 
step  which  the  thought  of  India  took,  goes  far  beyond  this,  and  is  of 
incalculable  importance.  It  builds  the  bridge  which  the  metaphysic 
of  the  via  negativa  needs,  to  enable  it  to  advance  to  the  work  of  con 
structing  an  ethic  and  a  theory  of  religion.  In  dealing  with  Par- 

1  "  Neti  "—it  is  not  thus.    See  Brih.  Up.  II.  3.  6.     (Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  vol. 
XV.,  p.  108):  III.  9.  26  (ib.  pp.  148, 149) :  IV.  2.  4  (ib.  p.  160) :  IV.  4.  22  (ib.  p.  180) :  IV.  5. 15  (ib. 
p.  185). 

2  Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  vol.  XXXVIII.,  p.  157.— Cf.  Max  Muller,  Three  Lectures 
on  the  Feddnta  Philosophy,  p.  84. 

3  "  •  In  the  beginning,  my  dear,  there  was  that  only  which  is  (TO  ov)  one  only,  without 
a  second.    Others  say,  in  the  beginning  there  was  that  only  which  is  not  (TO  /LCT)  6i>)  one 
only,  without  a  second ;  and  from  that  which  is  not,  that  which  is  was  born. 

'  But  how  could  it  be  thus,  my  dear  ? '  the  father  continued.  '  How  could  that  which  is 
be  born  of  that  which  is  not  ?  No,  my  dear,  only  that  which  is,  was  in  the  beginning,  one 
only,  without  a  second. 

'  It  thought,  may  I  be  many    .    .    .' " 

— .KTiand.  Up.  VI.  2. 1,  2,  3.  (Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  vol.  L,  p.  93.— Cf.  Max  Muller, 
Three  Lectures  on  the  Veddnta  Philosophy,  p.  35.) 

135 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

menides  two  reasons  were  pointed  out  which  prevented  his  philosophy 
from  becoming  to  the  Greek  race  a  guide  of  life.  Those  were  both, 
in  a  sense,  external  to  his  philosophy.  They  barred  the  way  against 
it  from  without.  But  if  these  had  both  been  absent,  there  was  still 
a  third  reason,  internal  to  the  system  of  Parmenides,  which  would 
have  tended  to  hold  it  back  from  becoming  a  guide  of  life.  If  I  am 
convinced  that  the  changing  and  the  manifold  are  illusion ;  and  if  by 
actual  experience  I  have  found  the  life  which  involves  these  to  be  very 
evil — so  evil  that  life  and  sorrow  are  one  same  thing;  and  if  from 
that  illusion  and  that  evil  I  wish  to  be  delivered  by  finding  rest  in  the 
One;  then,  whether  the  logic  of  my  philosophy  allows  it  or  not,  I 
must  believe  in,  some  sort  of  organic  connexion  between  myself  and  the 
One  by  withdrawal  into  which  or  absorption  into  which  I  am  to  find 
rest.  But  such  a  connexion  Parmenides  could  not  assert.  For,  as  we 
have  seen,  the  problem  of  the  self  simply  did  not  exist  for  him  at  all. 
To  the  teachers  of  India,  however,  the  problem  of  the  self  became  a 
keen  and  pressing  one.  And  so  they  were  able  to  make  the  great 
advance  which  rendered  possible  the  application  of  the  negative 
metaphysic  to  the  burdened  life  of  India : — they  asserted  a  connexion, 
nay  they  asserted  an  identity,  between  the  self  in  man  and  the  One 
which  is  the  true  and  only  reality. 

The  expedient  by  which  this  identification  of  the  self  of  man  with 
the  One — with  Brahman — was  effected,  was  very  violent.  But  it  was 
closely  in  line  with  the  general  procedure  of  the  negative  meta 
physic.  And  not  only  that ;  but  when  once  a  race  of  thinkers  to  whom 
the  problem  of  the  self  is  present,  have  taken  the  first  great  step  in 
the  via  negativa — have  made  the  advance  to  an  indeterminate  One — 
then  this  second  step  is  demanded  by  an  inexorable  necessity.  This 
necessity  the  clear-eyed  dialecticians  of  India  were  neither  unable  to 
see,  nor  afraid  to  face.  On  the  level  of  the  categories  which  abso 
lutely  disjoin  "is"  and  "is  not,"  Being  must  be  One;  no  sort  of 
exception  or  division  could  in  any  way  be  admitted.  Yet  the  self  had 
taken  such  a  place  in  their  thinking  that  it  could  not  be  summarily 
dismissed  as  this  fleeting  cloud,  or  that  fading  plant,  could  be  dis 
missed — namely,  as  illusion.  So  that  the  situation  had  come  to  be 
this. — Being  is  One,  without  division.  Yet  the  self  in  man  cannot 

136 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

be  dismissed.  Then  what  can  that  self  be?  It  cannot  be  considered 
either  as  a  part,  or  as  a  modification,  of  the  One.  That  would  be  to 
attribute  finitude  and  division  to  Brahman.  Nor  can  the  human  self 
be  anything  different  from  Brahman ;  for  Brahman  is  all  in  all,  "  one 
without  a  second."  In  a  word,  there  is  no  alternative  but  to  identify 
the  two.  And  that,  moreover,  not  in  the  sense  of  calling  the  human 
self  a  part  of  Brahman;  but  in  the  sense  of  an  absolute  identification 
— the  whole  of  Brahman  is  the  human  self.1 

But  do  not  the  manifest  finitude  and  dividedness  of  our  human 
experience  recalcitrate  against  such  an  identification?  Yet  the 
identification  must  be  made;  and  the  thinkers  who  lead  the  way  from 
Veda  to  Vedanta  cut  through  the  difficulty  by  a  piece  of  that  resolute 
surgery  which  the  metaphysic  of  the  via  negativa  knows  so  well  how  to 
practise.  They  conceive  the  soul  as  they  conceive  the  ultimate  and 
only  reality  with  which  it  is  to  be  identified — namely,  in  an  abstract 
way.  The  manifold  experiences  of  the  soul,  its  manifold  activities  of 
thought  and  of  sense,  of  memory  and  of  imagination — these  are  but 
a  veil,  and  behind  this  veil  dwells  the  true  self  of  which  we  can  say 
nothing  except  that  it  is.  The  apparent  dualism  of  the  relation  of 
subject  and  object,  whether  in  sense-experience  or  in  self-conscious 
ness,  is  ruled  out  altogether  from  the  true  Self.  "...  When 
the  Self  only  is  all  this,  how  should  he  see  another,  how  should  he 
smell  another,  how  should  he  taste  another,  how  should  he  salute 
another,  how  should  he  hear  another,  how  should  he  touch  another, 
how  should  he  know  another?  How  should  he  know  Him  by  whom 
he  knows  all  this?  That  Self  is  to  be  described  by  No,  no!  He  is 
incomprehensible  for  he  cannot  be  comprehended;  he  is  imperishable 
for  he  cannot  perish ;  he  is  unattached  for  he  does  not  attach  himself ; 
unfettered,  he  does  not  suffer,  he  does  not  fail.  How,  0  beloved, 
should  he  know  the  Knower?"2 

This,  too,  was  made  all  the  easier  by  the  very  term  which  was  used 
to  denote  the  self  or  soul.  The  term  atman  which  was  used  to  denote 
the  soul  of  man,  had  been  originally,  as  Max  Miiller  tells  us,  "  a  mere 
pronoun  free  from  any  metaphorical  taint,  and  asserting  nothing 

i  Max  Miiller,  Three  Lectures  on  the  Vedanta  Philosophy,  pp.  90-92. 
2  Brth.  Up.  IV.  6.  15.    (Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  vol.  XV.,  p.  185.) 

137 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

beyond  existence  or  self-existence."  It  meant  ipse,  and  as  used  to 
express  the  essence  of  man  or  of  God,  its  idea  was  simply  ipseitas. 
Man  was  Giv  atman,  the  living,  and  God  was  Parama-atman,  the 
highest  ipse.  And  the  absolute  identity  of  these  two  abstract  essences 
was  not  hard  to  affirm. 

Thus,  then,  the  great  identification  was  made,  and  the  "  Tat  tvam 
asi" — "Thou  art  it" — and  the  "Aham  brahmasmi" — "I  am  Brah 
man  " — become  the  watchwords  of  this  second  main  step  in  the  logical 
evolution  of  the  negative  metaphysic  in  India.  "  .  .  .  There 
fore  now  also,  he  who  thus  knows  that  he  is  Brahman,  becomes  all 
this,  and  even  the  Devas  cannot  prevent  it,  for  he  himself  is  their  Self. 
Now  if  a  man  worships  another  deity  [i.e.,  a  Deity  external  to  the 
Self  in  him]  thinking  the  deity  is  one  and  he  another,  he  does  not 
know.1  .  .  .  He  who  perceives  therein  [in  the  "  ancient, 
primeval  Brahman"]  any  diversity,  goes  from  death  to  death."2 

And  with  this  the  way  was  prepared  for  the  advance  to  ethics  and 
to  religion.  A  self  which  could  be  called  God,  but  which  could  also 
be  called  man,  was  left  standing.  But  the  finite,  the  manifold,  the 
changeable,  were  expelled  from  reality  and  cast  into  the  limbo  of 
vanity  and  nothingness.  "  In  one  half  verse,"  says  the  Vedantist,  "  I 
shall  tell  you  what  has  been  told  in  thousands  of  volumes : — Brahman 
is  true,  the  world  is  false,  man's  soul  is  Brahman  and  nothing  else. 
There  is  nothing  worth  gaining,  there  is  nothing  worth  enjoying, 
there  is  nothing  worth  knowing  but  Brahman  alone;  for  he  who 
knows  Brahman,  is  Brahman."3 

With  this,  then,  the  thought  of  the  Vedantists  went  forward  on  its 
great  way,  to  be  the  guide  of  life  and  of  religion,  not  to  India  alone 
but  to  lands  even  more  populous.  Upon  that,  however,  as  we  are 
chiefly  concerned  with  the  inner  logical  movement  of  the  metaphysic 
of  the  negative  tendency,  we  cannot  here  dwell  at  any  length.  But  a 
hint  at  the  vast  width  of  that  guidance  and  at  its  profound  signifi 
cance  in  human  history,  may  be  given  by  a  brief  reference  to  two 

1  Brfli.  Up.  I.  4. 10.    (Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  vol.  XV.,  p.  88.) 

2  Brih.  Up.  IV.  4. 19  (cf.  18— Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  vol.  XV.,  p.  179). 

3  Max  Miiller,  Three  Lectures  on  the  Veddnta  Philosophy,  pp.  172, 173.    Cf .  the  King's 
statement    of    the  vanity   of    life,   in   the  beginning  of    the   Maitrayana-Brahmana- 
Upanishad.    (Sacred  Books  of  the  East,  vol.  XV.,  p.  288  seq.) 

138 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

things.  The  first  of  these  is  seen  in  the  "  Forest  Schools  "  of  Brah- 
manism.  When  a  man's  hair  had  become  white  and  he  saw  his 
children's  children,  then  he  withdrew  to  the  forest.  The  Vedic  hymns 
which  hitherto  had  been  to  him  so  absolutely  sacred  and  so  absolutely 
unquestioned,  were  replaced  by  the  negative  and  abstract  theology  of 
the  Upanishads.  And  instead  of  the  careful  ceremonial  observances 
of  his  earlier  life,  and  its  performance  of  civic  and  domestic  duties, 
he  sought  only  to  free  himself  from  the  personal  and  the  individual, 
and  thus  to  find  his  true  self  in  the  Eternal  Self,  in  the  One,  in 
Brahman;1  sought,  in  a  word,  to  verify  in  life  that  which  the 
Upanishads  taught  him  as  theory — Tat  tvam  asi,  thou  art  it.  The 
second  is  seen  in  an  ethical  teaching  which  went  far  beyond  the 
bounds  of  India.  Gautama  had  been  trained  in  the  negative  meta- 
physic  of  Hinduism.  And  though  he  spoke  later  like  one  who  has 
repudiated  all  metaphysic,  yet  it  is  fair  to  say  that  his  doctrine  of 
Nirvana  expresses  the  ultimate  ethical  implication  of  the  metaphysic 
of  the  Vedanta.  The  very  intensity  of  his  compassion  for  a  life 
which  is  essentially  vain  led  him  to  make  his  moral  teaching  as  abso 
lutely  negative  as  a  moral  teaching  inspired  by  compassion  well  can 
be.  Indeed  the  morality  whose  goal  is  Nirvana  is  so  negative  that 
there  is  no  place  in  it  even  for  asceticism;  or  if  there  is,  it  is  only 
as  a  means  in  subduing  Trishna.2  For  the  extirpation  of  Trishna  is 
the  cessation  of  the  formation  of  Karma.  And  with  that  Nirvana  is 
gained. 

/ 

Thus  in  India  the  negative  tendency  worked  through  the  process 
of  its  logical  evolution  and  entered  upon  the  full  work  of  a 
philosophy.  It  seems  indeed  a  far  cry  from  Veda  to  Yedanta.  The 
brightness  of  the  early  Aryan  hymns  which  rejoice  to  watch  Indra 
"  cleaning  the  mountains  "  or  "  rousing  his  strength  in  a  moment  like 
the  whirlwind  rushing  along  with  thundering  clouds,"  and  are  glad 
at  the  presence  of  the  Dawn,  "  the  mother  of  the  morning  clouds, 
clad  in  her  garments  of  light,"  "  shining  on  us  like  a  young  wife,  rous- 

1  See  Max  Miiller,  Origin  and  Growth  of  Religion,  (Hibbert  Lectures),  p.  364  seq. 
Cf.  Three  Lectures  on  the  Veddnta  Philosophy,  pp.  19,  20. 

2  Trishna— desire,  yearning,  thirst ;  whatever  causes  life  to  be  a  process  of  activity. 

139 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

ing  every  living  being  to  go  to  his  work,"1 — this  seems  far  separated 
from  the  grey,  worn  thought  of  the  Upanishads.  Yet  we  have  seen 
that  the  process  which  led  from  the  one  to  the  other  was  a  process  of 
thorough  logical  continuity.  When,  in  a  Hindu  family,  the  young 
son  was  being  trained  in  the  strictest  Vedic  orthodoxy  while  the 
grandfather  dwelt  apart  in  the  forest  meditating  upon  a  theology  in 
which  the  Vedic  deities  could  find  no  place,  this  was  not  mere  incon 
sistency  or  contradiction.  It  was  the  symbol  of  the  connexion 
between  the  early  and  the  late  stages  of  a  single  development. 
Indeed  the  Vedantists  and  the  Eleatics  are  alike  proofs  that  in  all 
the  history  of  thought  there  are  few  logicians  so  consequent,  few 
dialecticians  so  strict,  as  those  whose  fate  it  is  to  conduct  from  its 
premisses  to  its  conclusion  the  ratiocination  of  the  negative 
philosophy. 

And  yet  for  Vedantist  and  Eleatic  alike  there  remained  a  great 
problem.  Each  regarded  reality  from  a  given  point  of  view — that  of 
the  categories  of  Being.  Each  developed  the  ultimate  consequence  of 
that  point  of  view:  the  Eleatic  by  a  curt  intellectual  argument  of 
incisive  and  summary  completeness;  the  Vedantist  by  a  vaster  and 
more  commanding  process  which  touched  the  whole  of  life.  Each 
came  to  the  inevitable  conclusion:  reality  is  an  indivisible  and 
changeless  One;  the  Many,  an  illusion.  But  that  at  once  raises  the 
question :  "  If  reality  is  a  changeless  and  indivisible  One,  how  can  it 
give  rise  to  even  an  illusory  appearance  of  a  manifold?" 

And  that  question  received  no  satisfactory  answer  from  either 
school.  Zeno,  to  whom  the  matter  was  a  purely  intellectual  one, 
replies  cheerfully  enough :  "  Your  experience  of  a  manifold  and  of 
change  must  be  an  illusion;  for,  as  I  can  show  you,  such  an  experi 
ence  involves  the  most  absurd  contradictions."  But  that  does  not 
meet  the  case.  Granted  that  my  experience  is  an  illusion,  still  how 
does  even  an  illusory  experience  of  change  and  of  manifoldness  come 
to  be  at  all,  when  reality  is  a  One,  unchanging  and  indivisible  ? 

i  See  the  hymn  to  Indra,  translated  by  Max  Miiller,  Origin  and  Growth  of  Religion 
(Hibbert  Lectures),  pp.  287-289;  and  the  hymn  to  the  Dawn  in  the  second  edition 
(London,  1868)  of  his  Chips  from  a  German  Workshop,  vol.  I.,  pp.  36,  37.  These  may  also 
be  found  in  "  The  Hymns  of  the  Rigveda  translated  with  a  popular  commentary  "  by 
Ralph  T.  H.  Griffith ;  the  hymn  to  Indra  (R-V.  IV.  17)  in  vol.  II.  (Benares,  1890),  pp.  118, 
119 ;  the  hymn  to  the  Dawn  (R-V.  VII.  77)  in  vol.  III.  (Benares,  1891),  p.  97. 

140 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

Nor  can  the  Vedantist  find  any  satisfactory  way  of  escape. 
"  AJiam  Irahmasmi"  he  says,  "  I  am  Brahman."  But  if  so,  whence 
come  the  limitations  under  which  the  self  in  man  labours?  The 
answer  is,  that  they  are  due  to  the  Upadhis — the  obstructions.1  But 
whence  come  these?  The  answer  is,  once  more,  from  Avidya, 
nescience.  And  Avidya  comes  to  be  conceived,  not  merely  as 
personal  ignorance,  but  a  great  independent  cosmical  power,  which 
is  able  for  a  time  to  overshadow  Brahman  itself.2  But  how  can 
Avidya  thus  affect  Brahman,  who  is  all  in  all,  "  one  without  a 
second,"  subject  to  nothing  outside  it,  because  there  is  nothing  outside 
it?3  The  Vedantist  can  only  answer  that  it  is  so.4  And  when 
pressed  as  to  how  such  a  thing  can  be  so,  he  can  only  fall  back  on  the 
plan  of  Zeno ;  he  can  only  attempt  to  involve  his  adversary  in  a  self- 
contradiction.  It  is  self -contradictory,  he  urges,  to  seek  to  know  what 
Avidya  is.  It  is  as  though  a  man  should  endeavour  to  see  darkness  by 
means  of  a  far-shining  torch.5 

Here,  then,  is  the  great  theoretical  or  scientific  difficulty  of  the 
metaphysic  of  the  via  negativa.  The  world  of  manifoldness  and 
change  refuses  to  be  driven  out  of  court.  Whether  as  real  or  as 
illusory,  it  demands  to  be  accounted  for. 

And  this  indicates  to  us  what  we  must  next  do.  We  are  attempt 
ing  to  see  how  this  metaphysic  has  behaved  in  the  field  of  the  history 
of  philosophy,  in  order  that  thereby  we  may  get  at  its  inner  move 
ment  and  genuine  significance.  We  must,  then,  turn  next  to  some 
instance  where  it  felt  the  full  weight  of  the  problem  just  noticed, 
and  put  forth  its  whole  power  in  the  endeavour  to  solve  it. 

1  These  are,  as  Deussen  says  (On  the  Philosophy  of  the  Veddnta,  Bombay,  1893,  p.  12), 
"our  whole  psychological  apparatus."    Cf.  the  same  author's  System  des  Veddnta  (Leip 
zig,  1883),  S.  326  seq. 

2  Max  Miiller,  Three  Lectures  on  the  Veddnta  Philosophy,  p.  97.    Avidya  in  this  sense 
came  later  to  be  called  May&  (ibid.  p.  128). 

3  Ibid.  p.  97. 
*  Ibid.  p.  97. 

5  Ibid.  p.  99.— Cf.  Deussen 's  "...    bleibet  nichts  ubrig,  als  an  die  Negativitat  de 
Begriffes  der  Avidya  zu  erinnern."— Das  System  des  Veddnta  (Leipzig,  1883),  S.  326. 


141 


THE   MBTAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

(r) 

Such  an  instance  we  shall  find  by  turning  to  one  of  those  sad 
periods  in  our  history,  where  the  student,  for  the  pity  and  the  anger 
which  gather  at  his  heart,  scarcely  can  keep  his  way.  The  great  age 
of  Greece  was  past.  The  work  of  the  Greek  race,  as  a  race,  had  long  been 
accomplished  in  East  and  in  West.  Rome  herself  was  coming  to  the 
worst  hours  of  her  evil  day.  Life  was  a  burden;  a  burden  met  by 
the  few  with  the  last  wantonness  of  luxury,  by  the  many  with  the 
dumb  and  hopeless  patience  which  is  the  only  refuge  of  the  oppressed 
when  the  methods  of  revolutionary  madness  are  not  possible.  The 
religious  instinct  was  coming  forward  in  its  most  negative  form; 
namely,  as  a  profound  and  passionate  craving  for  deliverance  from 
the  evils  and  vicissitudes  of  life,  from  the  perils  and  changes  and 
agonies  of  the  world.  And  along  with  this,  science  had  entered  upon 
a  decrepid  and  decadent  old  age.  Its  instruments  for  carrying  the 
manifold  and  the  changing  back  into  unity  and  eternity  were  as  weak 
as  the  religious  yearning  for  the  One  and  the  Eternal  was  strong. 
Under  such  circumstances  it  is  no  wonder  that  the  metaphysic  of  the 
via  negativa  once  more  became  dominant  among  men. 

But  with  all  this  there  went  another  fact.  The  manifold  world 
could  scarcely  be  dismissed  as  Zeno  and  the  Vedantists  had  dismissed 
it.  For  the  period  now  in  question  was  the  old  age  of  a  great 
civilisation.  Many  generations  of  labour,  of  culture,  of  splendid 
achievement,  of  orderly  polity  and  developing  institutions,  had  fixed 
and  confirmed  the  hold  of  the  world  upon  the  minds  of  men.  And  so 
it  is  just  here,  in  thife  troubled  battle-ground  upon  the  edge  of  dark 
ness,  where  the  religion  and  the  science  of  the  ancient  world  were 
going  down  to  death  together,  clad  in  monstrous  garments  of  the 
East — just  here  in  the  spiritual  confusions  which  centred  in  Alexan 
dria  and  in  Syria  but  whose  echoes  were  heard  even  in  Rome  and  in 
Athens — that  we  shall  find  the  negative  philosophy  in  full  struggle 
with  its  own  great  theoretical  crux.  This  indeed  is  seen  within  the 
Christian  Church  as  well  as  without  it — in  the  Gnostics  as  well  as 
in  the  Neo-Platonists.  But  it  is  with  the  latter,  whose  thought  is 
seen  at  its  greatest  in  the  system  of  Plotinus,  that  we  shall  find  the 
logic  of  the  situation  most  conveniently  shown. 

142 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

• 

On  the  one  hand,  Plotinus  holds  firmly  to  the  negative  or 
abstract  view  of  the  One.  The  One  is  unity  without  multiplicity, 
pure  Being  without  change  or  becoming ;  nay,  indeed,  it  is  "  beyond  " 
even  the  category  of  Being.  "It  neither  is"  he  says,  "nor  is  it 
something,  nor  is  it  anything,  but  it  is  over  all.  All  the  categories 
are  negatived;  it  has  no  magnitude,  is  not  infinite."1 

And  yet,  in  the  very  next  sentences,  he  goes  on  to  say  that  the 
One  is  "  the  eternal  source  of  virtue  and  the  source  of  divine  love, 
around  which  all  moves,  by  which  everything  directs  its  course,  in 
which  vovs  and  self -consciousness  ever  have  their  beginning  and 
their  end."  In  a  word  he  allows  a  place  for  the  manifold  world ;  and 
views  it  as  in  some  way  having  its  source  in  the  One. 

Here,  then,  is  the  very  situation  which  we  wished  to  find — an 
instance  in  which  the  negative  metaphysic,  while  holding  to  its  view 
of  the  One,  nevertheless  finds  a  place  for  the  world  of  manifoldness 
and  change.  Let  us  ask,  then,  by  what  means  Plotinus  accomplished 
this.  What  were  his  fundamental  logical  expedients? 

They  were  mainly  two.  One  was  the  theory  of  emanation.  This, 
however,  in  spite  of  the  great  place  which  it  took  in  the  thinking  of 
that  age,  is  little  more  than  a  metaphor;  and  indeed  only  by  meta 
phors2  was  it  made  to  convey  any  intelligible  meaning. 

But  the  other  was  one  of  the  most  ingenious  logical  devices  ever 
hit  upon  by  the  contriving  intellect  of  man.  Plotinus  sets  up  the 
idea  of  a  sort  of  one-ended  relation — or  rather  of  a  relation,  all  of 
whose  motion  is  in  one  direction.  As  between  the  two  terms  of  the 
relation,  it  is  a  relation  when  you  go  from  the  lower  to  the  upper. 
But  when  you  go  from  the  upper  to  the  lower,  it  is  no  relation  at  all. 

i  Enn.  VI.  Bk.  IX.— To  deal  systematically  with  Plotinus,  one  would  have  to  ask  first 
how  he  came  to  his  view  of  the  One  as  indeterminate.  The  answer  would  show  us  some 
thing  new  in  the  history  of  the  negative  tendency  ;  new,  however,  not  in  character,  but 
only  in  swiftness  of  movement.  For  Plotinus  reached  his  view  of  the  One,  not  by  an 
unsparing  dialectic  argument  working  out  the  implications  of  a  realistic  beginning,  but 
by  concentrating  such  argument  into  the  immediate  affirmation  of  an  intellectual 
intuition  which  apprehends  the  unity  of  experience  and  sets  that  unity,  as  the  true  reality 
over  against  the  particular  and  finite.  (See  Erdmann,  Hist.  Philos.  Eng.  tr.,  vol.  I.,  p. 
239,  and  compare  the  excellent  discussion  in  Caird's  Evolution  of  Theology  in  the  Greek 
Philosophers.)  For  our  present  purpose,  however,  it  is  not  necessary  to  go  into  this. 

zl£.g.,  the  snow  emits  cold ;  and  yet  the  snow  remains  itself,  identical,  undiminished. 
So,  too,  a  luminous  body  with  its  light,  or  a  flower  with  its  fragrance. 

143 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

To  the  lower  term  or  member  it  is  a  relation,  the  lower  being 
dependent  upon  the  higher  for  its  whole  existence  and  meaning.  But 
to  the  higher  it  is  not  a  relation  at  all,  in  any  sense  which  imposes 
metaphysical  obligation  or  responsibility.  "  It  is  that,"  says  Plotinus, 
of  the  One  conceived  as  the  Good,  "  on  which  all  depends,  and  which 
all  things  desire  and  have  as  principle,  and  which  they  are  all  in  want 
of,  while  it  itself  has  lack  of  nothing,  is  sufficient  for  itself,  and  is 
the  measure  and  limit  of  all;  which  out  of  itself  gives  the  rovs,  and 
essence,  and  soul,  and  life,  and  the  activity  of  reason.  .  .  .  But 
it  is  itself  by  no  means  that  of  which  it  is  the  principle/'1 

Thus,  in  Plotinus,  the  negative  tendency  wrestles  with  its  own 
great  theoretical  shortcoming.  A  sort  of  reality  is  given  to  the 
manifold  world.  And  at  the  same  time  the  One  remains  nearly, 
though  not  quite,  in  accord  with  the  negative  conception  of  it.  It 
has  ceased,  indeed,  to  be  "  all  in  all."  But  at  any  rate  it  remains  a 
One  which  excludes  all  multiplicity,  and  is  changeless  and  self- 
sufficient. 

It  is  easy  enough  to  point  out  the  inadequacy  of  this  solution. 
Metaphors,  as  such,  are  not  metaphysic.  And  the  idea  of  something 
which  is  a  relation  of  B  to  A,  but  not  of  A  to  B,  can  only  be  called 
self -contradictory.  With  such  criticism,  however,  we  are  not  at  this 
point  concerned.  Our  business  here  is  to  learn  what  the  negative 
tendency  really  is  and  really  means;  and  to  learn  this  by  observing 
how  it  has  behaved  in  the  field  of  history. 

The  three  great  cases  so  far  examined  have  shown  us  what  the 
inner  movement,  and  the  genuine  meaning,  of  this  tendency  are. 
With  this  we  can  pass  on  intelligently  to  Spinoza.  But  first  we 
should  turn  for  a  moment  to  the  period  between  Plotinus  and  the 
beginnings  of  specifically  modern  philosophy.  For  among  the  various 
appearances  of  the  negative  tendency  in  that  period,  there  is  one,  the 
outline  of  which  will  give  us  a  convenient  summary  of  the  chief 
points  so  far  brought  to  light. 

i  Enn.  I.  Bk.  8. 


144 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OP    SPINOZA 


The  whole  mediaeval  period,  indeed,  is  one  vast  illustration  of 
this  last  and  deepest  of  the  distinctions  that  have  arisen  in  thought 
and  life  as  men  seek  to  make  themselves  at  one  with  ultimate  and 
eternal  reality.  And  that  whether  we  regard  the  men  of  thought,  or 
their  methods  of  thinking,  or  the  practical  life  which  in  part  they 
shaped  and  which  in  part  shaped  them  —  a  life  half  control  of  the 
world,  half  renunciation  of  the  world.  In  the  intense  and  passionate 
reasonings  of  Augustine  which  set  the  problems  and  laid  the  basis  for 
mediaeval  thought  ;  in  the  penetrating  and  radical  insights  of  Erigena  ; 
in  the  massive  thought  of  St.  Thomas,  where  the  doctrine  of  the 
simplicitas1  of  the  Divine  nature  crosses  and  thwarts  the  insight 
that  all  things,  and  all  the  determinations  of  things,  have  their  being 
and  their  home  in  God  ;2  in  Nicolas  of  Cusa,  whose  view  of  the  world 
may  be  taken  as  the  last  great  expression  of  the  mediaeval  spirit  :  —  in 
all  these  the  negative  tendency  is  seen,  one  hardly  knows  whether  to 
say  in  conflict  or  in  combination  with  its  opponents.  These  men  all 
knew  that  the  universal  is  the  principle  of  reality;  and  that  there 
fore  the  universal  of  universals  is  the  ultimate  object  of  all  science 
and  the  true  end  of  all  conduct.  Nor  were  they  blind  to  the  fact 
that  that  highest  universal,  that  final  unity  of  all  things,  must  be  a 
concrete  and  synthetic  principle,  the  source  and  home  and  law  of  all 
the  particulars  of  the  world.  But  in  attempting  to  reach  that  highest 
universal  they  were  exposed  —  for  reasons  which  we  shall  see  later,3 

1  This  simplicitas  is  a  oneness  which  excludes  diversity.    Diversity  must  be  excluded 
from  the  Divine  nature  ;  for  else  the  Divine  nature  would  be  a  "  compositum,"  and  "  omne 
compositum  postering  est  suis  componentibus  et  dependens  ex  eis."    Moreover  "  omne 
compositum  causam  habet."    (See  Summa  Theol.  I.  3.  7  ;  and  cf.  I.  11.  1.—  "unum  non 
addit  supra  ens  rem  aliquam,  sed  tantum  negationem  divisionis"  ;   cf.  also  Contra 
Gentiles,  Bk.  I.  cap.  18.) 

2  This  may  fairly  be  called  the  deepest  insight  in  the  philosophy  of  St.  Thomas.    It 
may  be  seen,  for  instance,  by  taking  together  the  following  doctrines  and  considering  the 
consequences  of  their  synthesis.—  (1)  God  has  "  propriam  cognitionem  de  omnibus  rebus." 
(Contra  Gentiles,  I.  50.—  cf.  67-71—  and  cf.  also  the  parallel  passages  in  the  Summa  Theol. 
e.g.,  I.  14.  9-13.)      (2)  Scientia  Dei  est  causa  rerum.    (Summa  Theol.  I.  14.  8.)     (3)  But 
"  int  elligere  "  is   "the  activity  or  energising  (actus)  of  an  intelligence  which  exists  in 
itself  and  does  not  pass  over  into  anything  extrinsic  to  it,  as,  for  instance,  heating  passes 
over  into  that  which  is  heated."  (Contra  Gentiles,  I.  45.  1.)—  I  have  attempted  at  a  later 
page  to  work  this  out  more  fully  (infra,  pp.  336-341). 

3  Infra,  pp.  218,  219. 

11  145 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

were  specially  exposed — to  the  temptation  which  always  waits  upon 
that  endeavour:  the  temptation  to  have  recourse  to  the  simple  and 
easy  expedient  of  stripping  away  from  the  given  particulars  their 
differentiating  peculiarities  and  retaining  only  the  common  element. 
Such  a  process,  as  it  ascends  through  the  stages  of  widening  univer 
sality,  strips  away  all  determinations,  and  leaves  us  at  the  end  with 
an  altogether  abstract  and  empty  Absolute.  In  the  presence  of  such 
an  Absolute,  if  you  are  possessed  by  the  instinct  and  passion  of 
religion,  there  is  but  one  type  of  religion  still  open  to  you — the 
mystical.  And  if  you  have  felt  keenly  the  imperfection  and  the 
sorrows  of  the  world,  you  may  refuse  to  grieve  that  your  logic  calls 
you  and  your  fellows  to  such  a  goal;  indeed,  in  bringing  you  to  that 
goal,  your  sense  of  the  evil  of  the  world  has  probably  been  more 
influential  than  your  logic. 

But  over  those  great  names  we  must  pass.  To  two  of  them  we 
shall  return  later,  but  here  we  must  confine  ourselves  to  a  single 
mediaeval  instance;  one,  however,  which  in  interest  and  attraction 
yields  not  even  to  those.  In  the  thinking  of  those  "  dear  friends  of 
God,"  the  mediaeval  Mystics,  the  philosophy  of  the  via  negativa 
assumes  the  most  winning  form  which  it  has  ever  had  in  the  history 
of  man.  In  its  logical  movement  it  remains  true  to  type.  It  shows 
that  keen  dialectical  development  from  realistic  grounds  and 
methods,  which  has  characterised  so  many  of  its  great  historical 
appearances.  But  to  this  it  added  a  grace  that  has  won  the  reluctant 
hearts  of  later  and  more  earthly  generations.  And  the  height  of  its 
moral  passion  made  it  a  power  effective  for  the  regeneration  of  the 
religious  life  of  the  day — a  religious  life  externalised,  hardened, 
tending,  by  that  tragedy  which  waits  upon  priestly  churches,  to  lose 
itself  in  the  vast  forms  of  the  very  structure  which  it  had  been 
building  up  through  long  centuries  to  be  its  home. 

So  complete,  indeed,  is  the  evolution  of  the  negative  philosophy 
in  the  hands  of  the  Mystics  within  the  mediaeval  church,  that  we  shall 
find  united  in  their  thinking  nearly  all  those  main  features  and 
characters  which  so  far  we  have  discovered  by  studying  widely  diverse 
cases.  A  rapid  enumeration  of  the  main  points  in  their  teaching 

146 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

will  thus  afford  us  that  brief  summing  up  of  the  whole  position  which 
we  wish  to  make  before  passing  on  to  Spinoza. 

(1)  As  they  make  their  way  from  the  particulars  given  in 
experience  to  a  vision  of  the  highest  universal,,  they  do  not  take  the 
particulars  along  with  them  so  that  when  the  universal  is  gained 
the  particulars  are  seen  transformed  in  its  light  and  displayed  as 
genuine  elements  of  the  eternal.  Rather  they  gain  their  One  as  did 
Parmenides  and  the  Vedantists,  by  being  fully  in  earnest  with  the 
category,  or  point  of  view,  of  Pure  Being,  and  by  rigorously  carrying 
that  point  of  view  to  its  last  conclusions.  Eckhart  was  a  master  of 
the  Scholastic  learning;  what  he  did,  as  a  man  of  thought,  was  to 
give  complete  right  of  way  to  tendencies  and  methods  already 
.present  in  Scholastic  Realism,1  until  at  last  he  passes  beyond  the 
distinction  between  the  God  who  knows  and  the  begotten  or  created 
world  which  He  knows  to  that  ultimate  and  purely  unitary  Godhead 
in  which  there  is  neither  knowledge  nor  action  ( "  never  did  it  look 
upon  deed"),  neither  Father  nor  Son  nor  Holy  Ghost.  Windelband 
has  pointed  out  that  what  held  the  great  Schoolmen  back  from  work 
ing  out  this  development  themselves,  was  the  high  value  which 
Augustine  had  taught  them  to  set  upon  personality.2  But  with 
teachers  who  were  led,  by  just  their  keen  feeling  for  personality  and 
for  the  sorrows  and  evils  which  it  brings,  to  wish  for  its  suppression 
rather  than  for  its  encouragement,  this  check  was  taken  away,  and 
the  realistic  logic,  hastening  forward  to  its  conclusion,  came  to  the 
goal  where  all  logic  is  hushed.  The  ultimate  reality  has  no  deter 
mination  or  quality;  is,  in  Philo's  word,  anoio^.  Not  merely  is  it 
above  reason ;  but  even  Being,  the  emptiest  of  all  categories,  is  regarded 
as  too  particularised  a  conception  for  it,  and  it  is  declared  to  be 
beyond  Being.  It  is  not  "  Icht "  but  "  Nicht."  "  .  .  .  There 
fore,"  says  the  author  of  the  Theologia  Germanica,  "we  do  not  give 
a  name  to  the  Perfect,  for  it  is  none  of  these.  The  creature  as 
creature  cannot  know  nor  apprehend  it,  name  or  conceive 
it.  .  .  .  In  what  measure  we  put  off  the  creature,  in  the  same 
measure  are  we  able  to  put  on  the  Creator;  neither  more  nor  less."3 

i  Cf.  145, 146,  supra ;  and  218,  219,  infra.  2  Hist.  Philos.  tr.  Tufts  (1893),  p.  340. 

3  Theologia  Germanica,  tr.  Miss  Winkworth,  chap.  I. 

147 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

And  again  "...  He  who  findeth  satisfaction  in  aught  which 
is  this  and  that,  findeth  it  not  in  God;  and  he  who  findeth  it  in  God, 
findeth  it  in  nothing  else,  but  in  that  which  is  neither  this  nor  that, 
but  is  All.  For  God  is  One,  and  must  be  One,  and  God  is  All  and 
must  be  All.  And  now  what  is,  and  is  not  One,  is  not  God;  and 
what  is  and  is  not  All  and  above  All,  is  also  not  God,  for  God  is  One 
and  above  One,  and  All  and  above  All.  Now  he  who  findeth  full 
satisfaction  in  God,  receiveth  all  his  satisfaction  from  One  source, 
and  from  One  only,  as  One.  And  a  man  cannot  find  all  satisfaction 
in  God,  unless  all  things  are  One  to  him,  and  One  is  All,  and  some 
thing  [some  particular  thing]  and  nothing  (icht  und  niM)  are  alike."1 
(2)  But  no  sooner  has  this  point  been  reached  than  they  are 
face  to  face  with  their  great  problem — the  problem  set  by  the  mani 
fold  and  determinate  world,  whose  divine  and  angelic  orders  are 
declared  by  theology,  and  whose  earthly  facts  are  given  in  experi 
ence.  This  they  see  clearly,  and  set  themselves  to  the  task  of  deriving 
the  universe  of  particular  existences  from  that  ultimate  which  cannot 
even  be  described  as  Being,  which  can  as  well  be  called  non-Being 
as  Being.  In  that  still  and  formless  quiet,  a  movement  of  self- 
apprehension  and  self-utterance  is  declared  to  take  place.  Thus  arises 
a  double  outflowing.  First,  there  is  an  outflowing  of  that  which  is 
God,  and  in  this  the  Godhead  of  the  Christian  religion  comes  to  be. 
Secondly,  there  is  an  outflowing  of  that  which  is  not  God  (and  there 
fore  is  mere  nothing)  ;  by  this  all  the  world  of  creatures  arises.2  Into 
the  details  of  this  account  we  are,  however,  not  obliged  to  go.3  What 
concerns  us  is  the  fact  that  the  situation  itself  was  understood,  and 
was  deliberately  faced.  It  should  be  noted,  however,  that  the  very 
first  step  in  the  solution — the  postulated  self-apprehension  and  self- 

1  Theologia  Germanica,  tr.  Miss  Winkworth,  chap.  XLVL— Of  course,  in  the  Theologia, 
Germanica,  an  intensely  practical  book  written  in  the  Western  Church,  one  must  not  look 
for  the  negative  view  in  an  un  contradicted  form.    The  same  is  to  be  said  of  the  De 
Tmitatione  Christi. 

2  If  we  overlap  three  centuries,  and  the  sundering  gulf  of  the  Reformation,  we  find  the 
same  attempt  on  a  still  more  Titanic  scale  in  the  vast  imaginations  of  Bohme's  cosmogony 
and  cosmology.    But  one  must  note  how,  in  Bohme's  hostility  to  the  doctrine  of  a  creation 
out  of  nothing,  there  comes  forward  the  desire  for  a  positive  or  concrete  doctrine  of 
creation— i.e.,  a  doctrine  that  will  show  an  organic  relation  between  the  creature  and  the 
very  nature  of  God. 

3  References  to  Pfeiffer  are  given  by  Erdmann,  Hist.  Philos.  Eng.  tr.  vol.  I.,  p.  549. 

148 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OP    SPINOZA 

utterance — contradicts  the  original  account  of  the  ultimate  reality. 
It  is  a  salto  mortale;  the  gulf  is  impassable,  but  it  is  to  be  taken  as 
crossed. 

(3)  And  this  account  of  the  origin  of  the  world  of    creatures 
involves  a  view  of  the  self  in  man  similar  to  that  worked  out  by  the 
Vedantists.     For  the  account  given  of  that  outflowing  from  God  by 
which  the  creature  comes  to  be,  implies  that  what  makes  the  creature 
a   creature — what   distinguishes   him,   or   it,   from     God — is    really 
nothing  at  all.     If  we  could  strip  away  these  nothingnesses  and  get 
at  the  genuine  reality  of  the  creature — what    Eckhart  called    the 
"Spark"  the  point  or  apex  of  the  soul  which  is  divine  and  makes 
salvation  possible — that  reality  would  be  nothing  other  than  the  one 
eternal  reality  of  God.    "  '  Thou  sayest/  "  the  author  of  the  Theologia 
Germanica  imagines  the  objector  to  say,  " '  beside  the  Perfect  there 
is  no  substance,  yet  sayest  again,  that  somewhat  floweth  out  from  it: 
now  is  not  that  which  hath  flowed  out  from  it  something  beside  it?' 
Answer :     This  is  why  we  say,  beside  it,  or  without  it  [outside  of  it] 
there  is  no  true  Substance.    That  which  hath  flowed  forth  from  it,  is 
no  true  Substance  and  hath  no  Substance  except  in  the  Perfect,  but 
is  an  accident,  or  a  brightness  or  a  visible  appearance,  which  is  no 
Substance,  and  hath  no  Substance    except  in  the  fire    whence  the 
brightness  flowed  forth,  such  as  the  sun  or  a  candle."1 

(4)  Finally,  all    this   is    carried    forward    to  its    ethical    and 
religious  application.     These  nothingnesses    which   separate  us,   as 
creatures,  from  God — these  qualities  and  determinations,  this  being 
"here"  and  "now,"  which  make  us  to  be  creatures,  and  hide  from 
us  our  home  in  God — let  us  strip  them  away.    "  Thou  shalt  sink  thy 
thine-ness  and  thy  thine  shall  become  a  mine  in  his    mine,"    says 
Eckhart  to  the  soul2  in  describing  the  process  of  its  salvation;    a 
process  summed  up  in  that  virtue  of  Abgeschiederiheit,  in  which  by 
heroic  struggle  the  moveless  inner  divine  man  subdues  to  himself  the 

1  Miss  Winkworth's  translation,  chap.  I.— Note  the  Neo-Platonic  idea  of  emanation  in 
the  last  sentence,  contained,  characteristically,  in  a  metaphor.— Note  too  that  what  to  the 
Vedantist  was  an  express  view  of  the  self,  is  here  only  the  implication  regarding  the  self, 
of  the  general  doctrine  as  to  the  creature.       (Cf.  Erdmann,  Hist.  Philos.  Eng.  tr.  vol.  I., 
pp.  549,  550.) 

2  See  Erdmann,  Hist.  Philos.  Eng.  tr.  vol.  I.,  p.  552.     Cf.  the  reference  (p.  219  infra) 
to  Professor  Royce's  paper  on  Eckhart. 

149 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

outer  man  who  is  a  creature  of  desire  and  change ;  though  the  intense 
and  practical  character  of  Eckhart's  religious  endeavours  made  it  diffi 
cult  enough  for  him  to  remain  consistently  at  this  point  of  view.  The 
same  teaching,  though  again  with  the  same  qualification,  is  found  in 
the  Theologia  Germanica.  "  Now  mark :  when  the  creature  claimeth 
for  its  own  anything  good,  such  as  Substance,  Life,  Knowledge,  Power, 
and  in  short  whatever  we  should  call  good,  as  if  it  were  that,  or 
possessed  that,  or  that  were  itself,  or  that  proceeded  from  it — as 
often  as  this  cometh  to  pass,  the  creature  goeth  astray.  What  did  the 
devil  do  else,  or  what  was  his  going  astray  and  his  fell  else,  but  that 
he  claimed  for  himself  to  be  also  somewhat,  and  would  have  it  that 
somewhat  was  his,  and  somewhat  was  due  to  him?  This  setting  up 
of  a  claim,  and  his  I  and  Me  and  Mine,  these  were  his  going  astray, 
and  his  fall.  And  thus  it  is  to  this  day."1  "  Behold  on  this  sort 
must  we  cast  all  things  from  us,  and  strip  ourselves  of  them ;  we  must 
refrain  from  claiming  anything  for  our  own."2  "  For  if  the  left  eye 
be  fulfilling  its  office  toward  outward  things ;  that  is,  holding  converse 
with  time  and  the  creatures;  then  must  the  right  eye  be  hindered  in 
the  working"  [i.e.,  "seeing  into  eternity"].3  "Let  no  one  suppose, 
that  we  may  attain  to  this  true  light  and  perfect  knowledge,  or  life 
of  Christ,  by  much  questioning,  or  by  hearsay,  or  by  reading  and 
study,  nor  yet  by  high  skill  and  great  learning.  Yea,  so  long  as  a 
man  taketh  account  of  anything  which  is  this  or  that,  whether  it  be 
himself,  or  any  other  creature;  or  doeth  anything,  or  frameth  a 
purpose,  for  the  sake  of  his  own  likings,  or  desires,  or  opinions,  or 
ends,  he  cometh  not  unto  the  life  of  Christ."4  "Be  assured,  he  who 
helpeth  a  man  to  his  own  will,  helpeth  him  to  the  worst  that  he  can."5 
And  with  this  may  be  compared  the  great  lesson  De  contemptu 
omnium  vantitatum  mundi  which  a  Kempis  is  never  weary  of  incul 
cating,  and  the  lesson  that  we  must  withhold  our  minds  from  all  the 
creatures  in  order  that  we  may  find  the  Creator;  for  that  which  is 
not  God  is  nothing,  and  is  to  be  accounted  as  nothing. 

i  Miss  Winkworth's  translation,  chap.  II.  2  Ibid.  chap.  V. 

3  Ibid.  chap.  VII.  4  Ibid.  chap.  XIX.  5  Ibid.  chap.  XXXIV. 


150 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 
V. 

Such  was  the  attempt,  in  the  thought  and  in  the  life  of  the  older 
world,  to  rise  by  the  negative  way  from  appearances  to  reality.  The 
four  cases  which  we  have  examined  show  the  inner  logic  of  that 
endeavour;  show  the  essential  contradiction  which  vexes  it;  and  show 
something  more — to  what  practical  efficiency  in  evil  days,  and  to 
what  clear  shining  of  heavenly  light  in  the  soul,  it  was  possible  for 
men  to  rise  by  that  bleak  and  apparently  hopeless  road  of  denial. 

When  we  leave  those  ages  behind  us  and  come  to  our  own,  it  seems 
as  if  the  last  possibility  of  mystic  thought  or  life  had  departed.  The 
air  is  different.  For  good  and  for  evil,  the  world  has  made  us  its 
own.  And  yet  Mysticism,  alike  in  its  logic  and  in  its  life,  has  had  its 
place  among  us ;  and  in  both  aspects  has  been  surprisingly  true  to  its 
ancient  type.  As  a  practical  spirit  it  has  passed,  as  of  old,  "like 
night  from  land  to  land,"  in  unexpected  places  finding  out  its  own, 
leaving,  to  mark  its  course,  here  and  there  a  starry  name  but  usually 
only  the  atmosphere  of  its  peace.  In  the  Church  of  England,  in 
Germany — though  not  now  as  once — and  specially  among  the 
Friends,  it  has  laid  its  finger  upon  its  chosen,  and  in  them  has  given 
to  the  modern  world  well-nigh  its  most  admirable  type  of  character. 
And  once  at  least  it  moved  with  terrific  energies;  many  an  English 
man,  in  the  civil  war,  struck  hard  with  the  sword,  and  showed  no ' 
mercy  in  victory,  nor  lost  hope  in  defeat,  because  he  had  in  him  as 
an  inner  fire  the  same  instinct  that  in  earlier  days  led  men  to  the 
silent  life — the  instinct  for  the  immediate  ascent  of  the  soul  to  God. 

On  the  -speculative  side,  the  history  is  easier  to  trace ;  for  there 
the  mystic  conception  of  ultimate  reality  came  forward  in  the  place 
determined  by  that  secular  logic  which  leads  philosophy  through  its 
epochs.  Hence  the  mystic  view  of  reality,  as  it  appeared  in  modern 
thought,  was  at  once  new  and  old:  old,  in  that  it  unconsciously 
repeated  an  ancient  situation  and  an  ancient  movement  of  thought — 
for  Mysticism  is  really  the  one  theology  of  which  men  ought  to  say 
"  semper  eadem  " ;  new,  in  that  it  is  original  and  independent,  arising 
from  its  own  modern  sources  and  moving  by  its  own  impulses.  It 
was  a  stage — a  stage  integral,  essential,  necessary — in  the  working 

151 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OP    SPINOZA 

out  of  a  scientific  process  which  began  with  the  beginning  of  the 
modern  world.  In  Greece  the  first  men  of  science  had,  as  we  have 
already  seen,  to  begin  at  the  very  beginning.  And  in  the  long-drawn 
carrying  out  of  the  attempt  which  they  initiated,  the  thought  of  Par- 
menides  not  merely  occupies  a  place;  it  occupies  a  place  logically 
inevitable,  performs  a  function  logically  necessary.  In  modern 
thought  there  has  been  something  very  similar.  Those  who  stood  at 
the  beginning  of  the  modern  period  held  it  necessary  that  science  and 
philosophy  should  do  their  work  all  over  again ;  should  go  back  to  the 
very  beginning  and  make  their  start  once  more  from  that  point; 
should,  from  the  very  bottom,  build  themselves  up  altogether  anew. 
And  the  long  working  out  of  the  endeavour  thus  initiated  proceeded, 
as  among  ancient  Greeks,  so  among  modern  Europeans,  with  strict 
logical  continuity.  In  the  latter  case,  as  in  the  former,  there  came  a 
point  where  the  negative  view  showed  itself  as  a  necessary  and 
inevitable  stage  in  the  logical  evolution.  And  at  that  point  stood 
Spinoza. 

But  the  life  of  the  first  era  of  modern  Europe  was  a  much  more 
complex  thing  than  that  of  the  age  in  which  Greek  science  began  to 
be.  This  is  reflected  in  the  way  in  which  the  negative  metaphysic 
takes  its  rise  in  Spinoza's  thought;  and  is  reflected  in  another 
thing  which  we  shall  have  to  study  a  little  later — the  way,  namely, 
in  which,  in  Spinoza's  thinking,  it  has  to  share  its  throne  with  its 
great  opponents,  as  with  Eleatics  and  Yedantists  it  had  not  to  do. 

For,  as  we  study  its  genesis  in  Spinoza,  the  first  factor  that  we 
find  is  a  moral  and  religious  one.  Experience,  as  he  tells  us  in  the 
remarkable  opening  pages  of  his  treatise  on  Method,1  had  taught  him 
that  "  all  the  usual  surroundings  of  social  life  are  vain  and  futile." 
Further  reflection  convinced  him  that  if  he  "could  really  get  to  the 
root  of  the  matter  "  he  "  would  be  leaving  certain  evils  for  a  certain 
good."  He  "  thus  perceived  that  he  was  in  a  state  of  great  peril " 
and  he  "compelled  himself  to  seek  with  all"  his  "strength  for  a 
remedy  however  uncertain  it  might  be ;  as  a  sick  man  struggling  with 

i  Tractatus  de  Intellectus  Emendatione,  I  have  followed  Elwes'  translation  (2nd  ed. 
revised)  of  Spinoza's  "Chief  Works,"  save  where  references  to  some  other  edition  or 
translation  are  given. 

152 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OP    SPINOZA 

a  deadly  disease,  when  he  sees  that  death  will  surely  be  upon  him 
unless  a  remedy  be  found,  is  compelled  to  seek  such  a  remedy  with 
all  his  strength,  inasmuch  as  his  whole  hope  lies  therein."  He  was 
able  to  see,  however,  what  the  source  of  all  these  evils  is,  and  so  in 
what  direction  the  way  of  escape  from  them  must  lie,  if  any  such  way 
of  escape  there  be.  "  All  these  evils,"  he  says,  "  seem  to  have  arisen 
from  the  fact  that  happiness  or  unhappiness  is  made  wholly  to  depend 
on  the  quality  of  the  object  which  we  love.  When  a  thing  is  not  loved, 
no  quarrels  will  arise  concerning  it — no  sadness  will  be  felt  if  it  perishes 
— no  envy  if  it  is  possessed  by  another — no  fear,  no  hatred,  no  dis 
turbances  of  the  mind.  All  these  arise  from  the  love  of  what  is 
perishable,  such  as  the  objects  already  mentioned  [riches,  fame, 
pleasures  of  sense].  But  love  toward  a  thing  eternal  and  infinite 
feeds  the  mind  wholly  with  joy,  and  is  itself  unmingled  with  any 
sadness,  wherefore  it  is  greatly  to  be  desired  and  sought  for  with  all 
our  strength." 

With  Spinoza  then,  as  with  Vedantist  and  Neo-Platonist  and 
medieval  Mystic,  it  is  primarily  a  moral  or  religious  passion  which 
sets  him  at  work.  It  is  a  passion  after  that  Eternal,  by  making  our 
home  in  which  we  shall  be  delivered  from  the  vanities  and  the  evils 
of  this  life.  But  if  we  are  to  understand  that  fact  aright,  we  must 
give  careful  heed  to  three  other  facts.  First,  when  a  man  undertakes 
a  scientific  task,  he  has  to  work  with  scientific  instruments  no  matter 
whether  the  interest  that  set  him  at  the  work  was  primarily  a  moral 
and  religious,  or  primarily  an  intellectual,  one;  and  therefore  the 
work  itself  must  in  the  first  instance  be  studied  and  be  judged  as 
science.  Secondly,  Spinoza's  was  a  mind  of  such  an  order,  that  his 
religious  interest  made  him  work  all  the  more  truly  in  the  scientific 
spirit.  Just  because  the  stake  was  so  great,  therefore  the  science 
must  be  as  accurate  as  possible.  Just  because  it  was  a  matter  of  life 
and  death  in  the  deepest  sense  of  those  words,  therefore  logic  must 
have  its  uttermost  right  and  do  its  uttermost  work.  But,  thirdly, 
even  more  than  that  is  true.  Spinoza's  nature  was  as  truly  scientific 
as  it  was  truly  religious.  He  was  animated  by  the  scientific  passion 
as  truly  as  by  the.  religious.  He  had  the  instinct  for  rationalising  the 
world,  as  truly  as  the  longing  after  an  eternal  object  for  his  love. 

153 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

All  these  three  counts  require  us  to  consider  his  system  as  a  piece  of 
rational  science — as  a  logical  structure.  And  in  doing  that,  our 
first  endeavour  must  be,  with  him  as  with  Parmenides  or  Eckhart,  to 
understand  the  logical  situation  in  which  he  found  himself  and  which 
gave  him  his  point  of  departure.  What  that  situation  was  we  may 
see  by  considering  carefully  just  what  Descartes  had  done  in  his 
attempt  to  begin  at  the  very  beginning  and  to  build  up  thence  a 
science  which  should  be  trustworthy  because  from  beginning  to  end 
no  untested  material  had  been  admitted. 

Descartes,  then,  after  stripping  away  all  traditions,  all  doctrines, 
all  principles,  which  lie  in  any  way  open  to  doubt,  still  finds  one 
thing  which  emphatically  is.  It  so  truly  is,  that  even  in  attempting 
to  doubt  its  existence,  one  asserts  its  existence.  Cogito,  ergo  sum.  I, 
the  thinker,  am.  Or,  as  we  should  probably  say  nowadays: 
"  Thought  is." 

So  far,  good.  But  the  really  important  question  is :  What  did 
Descartes  do  with  the  cogito  when  he  had  got  it?  This  may  best  be 
seen  by  comparing  what  Descartes  did  with  what  a  later  philosophy 
did.  This  later  philosophy  perceived  that  in  the  cogito — in  all 
thought,  though  it  be  the  kind  of  thought  called  doubt,  or  even 
though  it  be  the  kind  involved  in  sense-perception — there  is  involved, 
on  the  one  hand,  a  subjective  consciousness,  and  on  the  other,  an 
objective  consciousness  in  which  certain  principles  are  operative. 
But  this  consciousness  of  objects  and  that  consciousness  of  self  are 
seen  to  be  correlative,  neither  being  possible  apart  from  the  other; 
so  that  they  constitute  together  a  consciousness  which  is  truly  one 
and  not  two.  •  This  consciousness,  then,  this  cogito,  in  which  many 
facts  and  operations  are  thus  present  in  one  self-conscious  grasp,  is 
a  true  and  veritable  Many-in-One ;  in  it  is  found  a  genuine  principle 
of  unity-in-diversity.  And  with  this,  the  problem  of  the  Many  and 
the  One  at  which  science  and  philosophy  have  been  labouring  from 
the  beginning,  comes  at  last  to  its  solution -in  the  conception  of  a 
supreme  self-consciousness,  or  spirit,  who  is  the  subject  of  the  world. 

Now  there  is,  it  is  true,  something  in  Descartes'  treatment  of  the 
cogito  which  looks  straight  in  this  direction.  And  that  something  a 
modern  student,  trained  in  the  school  of  Platonic  or  Hegelian  Ideal- 

154 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

ism,  would  at  once  seize  upon  as  the  deepest  and  most  valuable  insight 
of  the  Cartesian  philosophy.  It  lies  in  the  fact  that  to  Descartes  our 
highest  category  is  the  conception  of  God.  In  all  our  judging — when 
we  doubt  or  criticise,  when  we  find  things  to  be  imperfect  or  finite — 
there  is  involved  an  explicit  or  implicit  conception  of  a  being  perfect 
and  infinite;  only  through  the  conception  of  the  perfect  and  infinite 
can  we  judge  anything  to  be  finite  or  imperfect.  In  other  words,  our 
consciousness  of  God  is  the  impelling  element  in  all  our  knowledge. 
It  is,  so  to  speak,  the  vital  soul  of  the  cogito.  Without  it  there  could 
be  no  such  thing  as  knowledge  or  thinking  at  all.  r^ 

But  to  this  insight  that  an  explicit  or  implicit  consciousness  of 
God  constitutes  the  very  essence  of  the  cogito,  and  is  the  basis  of  all 
knowledge,  neither  Descartes  nor  his  age  could  do  justice.  Nor  was 
it  to  be  expected  that  they  should.  There  is  no  royal  road  to  meta- 
physic  as  reasoned  science.  If  men  are  to  use  a  higher  category  as 
an  assured  instrument  of  orderly  and  abiding  scientific  insight,  they 
must  first  work  their  way  through  the  stubborn  dialectic  of  the  lower 
categories.  So  it  was  in  Greek  philosophy;  and  the  case  was  not 
otherwise  with  the  philosophy  of  modern  Europe.  So  that  what  we 
must  deal  with  here  is  not  that  idealistic  Descartes  whom  a  Platonist 
or  a  Kantian  may  very  rightly  dig  up  out  of  the  Meditations;  it  is 
the  Descartes  whom  that  age  received;  and  in  particular  it  is  the 
Descartes  who  furnished  to  Spinoza  his  point  of  departure.  We  must 
inquire  very  carefully  what  that  Descartes  did  with  the  indubitable 
reality  which  he  had  found  even  in  the  midst  of  doubt — with  that 
vital  union  of  subject  and  object  which  he  summed  up  in  the  word 
cogito. 

And  first  we  must  notice  that  in  his  attempt  to  found  science  and 
philosophy  anew,  he  began  at  the  beginning  in  a  far  more  rudi 
mentary  sense  than  he  himself  imagined.  In  dealing  with  the 
cogito,  the  Descartes  that  we  are  here  concerned  with  drew  his  point 
of  view  and  his  principles  of  explanation  from  the  first  and  lowest 
of  the  families  of  the  categories.  He  went  to  the  categories  of  Being 
and  employed  in  particular  the  category  of  Substance;  adopted,  that 
is  to  say,  the  method  of  explanation  in  which  the  pure,  eternal, 
unchangeable,  uncompounded  Being  is,  in  some  way,  put  under  or 

1E5 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

behind  the  visible  and  changing  qualities  with  which  in  our  experi 
ence  we  have  directly  to  deal,  and  is  viewed  as  the  substrate  of  those 
qualities.  The  result  of  this  was  that  he  ended  by  splitting  the 
co git o  into  two.  That  is,  he  sharply  sundered  the  subjective  con 
sciousness  and  the  consciousness  of  objects.  Each  he  treated  by 
itself;  but  of  course,  since  they  were  viewed  as  co-ordinate  realities, 
used  the  same  category  and  followed  the  same  schema  in  each  case. 
In  dealing  with  the  subjective  consciousness,  he  conceived  the  ego, 
which  is  the  subject  of  the  cogito,  as  a  substance — a  "  thinking 
thing" — and  "  thought "  was  its  attribute.  Of  this  attribute,  the 
various  states  of  mind  (ideas,  feelings,  volitions,  and  so  on)  are 
modifications.  What  leads  him  to  this,  is  just  the  perception  that 
these  latter,  these  "  states  of  consciousness  "  which  he  comes  in  the 
end  to  call  modifications,  cannot  stand  alone.  They  are  not  self- 
intelligible.  Per  aliud,  non  per  se,  concipiuntur.  And  so  we  are 
referred  back,  and  back,  and  back,  until  we  come  to  something  which 
fulfils  the  great  requirement;  something  quod  per  se  concipitur. 
This  is  thought.  But  even  yet  Descartes  is  not  quite  satisfied. 
Thought  can  be  conceived  through  itself,  it  is  true.  But  yet,  there  is 
an  ego  which  is  the  subject  of  the  cogito;  an  ego  whose  essence  and 
nature  it  is  to  be  a  thinking  thing.  And  so  we  get  the  complete 
scheme: — the  substance  or  thinking  thing;  its  attribute,  thought; 
and  the  descending  orders  of  the  modifications  of  this  attribute — 
modes,  and  modes  of  modes,  and  modes  of  these  again  as  far  as  you 
choose  to  go.  Thus,  then,  Descartes  dealt  with  the  subjective  con 
sciousness.  But,  next,  he  finds  a  great  order  of  facts  or  qualities 
which  he  does  not  feel  able  to  assign  to  the  subjective  consciousness, 
and  these  he  simply  casts  out  of  the  cogito  altogether.1  Here  also 
the  same  line  of  reflexion  is  followed  out;  the  same  search  made 
after  something  which  can  stand  alone  and  be  conceived  through 
itself.  And  this  gives  us  the  same  general  form  on  this  side  as  on  the 
other: — a  substance  (body),  its  attribute  (extension),  and  the 
various  modifications  of  this  attribute. 

Furthermore,  these  two  spheres  are  quite  independent  of    each 
other.     Each  of  these  two  substances  can    exist,    and  be    conceived, 

1  See  especially  Meditation  VI. 
156 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

without  the  help  of  the  other.  Indeed  it  is  of  the  nature  of  sub 
stances  to  be  mutually  exclusive.1  And  the  attributes  are  as  radically 
opposed  to  each  other,  are  as  mutually  exclusive,  as  the  substances. 
Extension  is  not  conscious;  thought  is  not  extended.  In  a  word, 
whatever  thought  is,  that  extension  is  not ;  and  whatever  extension  is, 
that  thought  is  not.  If  anything  falls  within  one,  it  falls  without 
the  other. 

But  this  absolute  disjunction  plunges  us  at  once  into  difficulties. 
For  in  our  actual  experience  these  two  orders  of  being  most  certainly 
come  into  connexion  with  each  other.  I,  the  thinking  thing,  have 
an  experience  of  extended  things.  We  have,  then,  a  double  problem 
on  our  hands.  First,  an  empirical  problem:  By  what  expedient  is 
that  connexion  as  a  matter  of  fact  brought  about?  And  secondly,  a 
metaphysical  problem :  How,  ultimately,  is  the  possibility  itself  of 
that  connexion  to  be  accounted  for  ?  Descartes'  answer  to  the  former, 
seen  in  his  theory  of  the  passions  and  in  his  view  of  the  function 
of  the  pineal  gland,  need  not  concern  us  here.  But  his  answer  to 
the  latter  is  of  radical  importance. 

What  he  did  not  do,  in  this  answer,  was  to  remove  the  difficulty 
itself  by  recognising  the  organic  connexion  of  thought  and  the 
extended  world.  Gassendi  in  his  Objections  forced  Descartes  to  the 
point  where  to  a  student  of  to-day  this  recognition  seems  unavoid 
able.  But  it  was  beyond  the  power  of  the  philosophy  of  that  age  to 
make  the  recognition  in  any  vital  way.  A  few  sentences  from  the 
argument  between  Gassendi  and  Descartes  will  show  how  the  matter 
stood.  "  .  .  .  parceque  <Tun  cote,"  Descartes  had  said  in  the 
sixth  Meditation,2  "  j'ai  une  claire  et  distincte  idee  de  moi-meme,  en 
tant  que  je  suis  seulement  une  chose  qui  pense,  et  non  etendue,  et 

1  One  finds  such  statements  as,  for  instance,  the  following— "  Sed  jam  dicendum  est 
quo  pacto  ex  hoc  solo  quod  unam  substantiam  absque  altera  dart  &  distincte  intelligam, 
certus  sim  unam  ab  alia  excludi.    Nempe  haec  ipsa  est  notio  substantiae,  quod  per  se,  hoc 
est  absque  ope  ullius  alterius  substantiae  possit  existere,  nee  ullus  unquam  qui  duas 
substantias  per  duos  diversos  conceptus  percepit,  non  judicavit  illas  esse  realiter  dis- 
tinctas."    (Responsiones  quartae,  p.  124— Second  Elzevir  edition.)-Indeed  from  the  point 
of  view  of  "Being"  substances  must  be  mutually  exclusive.      This  Parmenides  saw 
clearly ;  and  then,  with  his  principle  that  in  the  real  there  is  no  "  is  not,"  leapt  at  once  to 
the  conclusion  that  the  real  is  one  indivisible  substance. 

2  Cousin's  edition  (Paris :  Levrault,  1824-26),  tome  I.,  p.  332.    In  the  Elzevir  edition,  the 
fifth  and  seventh  "Objections  and  Replies"  (the  fifth  being  the  discussion  with  Gassendi) 
are  given  as  an  Appendix. 

157 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

que  (Tun  autre  j'ai  une  idee  distincte  du  corps,  en  tant  qu'il  est 
seulement  une  chose  etendue  et  qui  ne  pense  point,  il  est  certain  que 
moi,  c'est-a-dire  mon  ame  par  laquelle  je  suis  ce  que  je  suis,  est  entiere- 
ment  et  veritablement  distincte  de  mon  corps,  et  qu'elle  pent  etre 
ou  exister  sans  lui."  Gassendi,  in  the  course  of  his  argument,  raises 
this  point,1  "  .  .  .  mais  suppose,  comme  vous  dites,  que  vous 
soyez  une  chose  qui  n'est  point  etendue,  je  nie  absolument  que  vous 
en  puissiez  avoir  1'idee.  Car,  je  vous  prie,  dites-nous  comment  vous 
pensez  que  1'espece  ou  1'idee  du  corps  qui  est  etendu  puisse  etre 
regue  en  vous,  c'est-a-dire  en  une  substance  qui  n'est  point  etendue  ?"2 
Descartes'  answer  is  rather  a  clever  parrying  of  the  difficulty  than  a 
solution  of  it. — "  Je  reponds  a  cela  qu'aucune  espece  corporelle  n'est 
regue  dans  1'esprit,  mais  que  la  conception  ou  1'intellection  pure  des 
choses,  soit  corporelles,  soit  spirituelles,  se  fait  sans  aucune  image 
ou  espece  corporelle."3  So  that  to  the  end  Descartes  held  to  the 
mutual  independence,  the  mutual  exclusiveness,  of  thought  and 
extension. 

And  what  he  did  do,  in  endeavouring  to  meet  the  difficulty,  was 
this.  He  made  the  two  substances,  of  which  extension  and  thought 
are  the  respective  attributes,  subordinate,  and  premised,  to  effect 
their  connexion  with  each  other,  a  third  substance  which  is  God. 
"  By  substance,"  he  says,  "  we  can  conceive  nothing  else  than  a  thing 
which  exists  in  such  a  way  as  to  stand  in  need  of  nothing  beyond 
itself  in  order  to  its  existence.  And,  in  truth,  there  can  be  conceived 
but  one  substance  which  is  absolutely  independent,  and  that  is 
God.  .  .  .  Created  substances,  however,  whether  corporeal  or 
thinking,  may  be  conceived  under  this  common  concept  [of  sub 
stance]  for  these  are  things  which  in  order  to  their  existence,  stand  in 
need  of  nothing  but  the  concourse  of  God."4  Thinking  substance  and 
extended  substance,  then,  are  not  independent  of  God.  But  their 
independence  of  each  other  Descartes  maintains  stoutly  and  to  the  end. 

It  was  this  thinking,  then,  and  the  logical  situation  which  arose 

1  With  regard,  as  he  points  out,  not  to  "corps  en  general,"  but  to  "corps  massif  et 

grOSSlGF- 

2  Ed.  cited,  tome  II.,  p.  224. 

3  Ed.  cited,  tome  II. ,  p.  297. 

4  Principles,  I.  51,  52,  tr.  Veitch  (Blackwood). 

158 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

out  of  this  thinking,  that  furnished  to  Spinoza  his  scientific  point  of 
departure.  True,  Spinoza  brought  with  him  elements  which  ortho 
dox  Cartesians  would  have  repudiated  with  becoming  severity- 
elements  from  ben  Maimon;  from  Chasdai  Creskas;  especially  from 
Ibn  Ezra,  and  through  him  from  that  heretical  Jew  pantheist, 
Avicebron;  possibly  even  from  Bruno.  True  also,  he  brought  to  the 
Cartesian  philosophy,  deep  spiritual  passions  of  a  kind  to  which  it 
was  a  stranger.  And  true,  moreover,  he  often  states  in  strangely 
sharp  and  pointed  language  his  opposition  to  this  or  that  tenet  of 
Descartes.1  But  the  fact  remains  that  the  logical  situation  created 
by  Cartesianism  was  Spinoza's  scientific  point  of  departure;  and 
that  by  Spinoza's  work  the  fundamental  lines  in  the  movement  of 
Cartesian  thought  were'  carried  forward  to  their  logical  conclusion. 
That  he  himself  had  no  special  intention  to  do  this ;  that  he  did  not 
regard  his  own  system  as  standing  in  any  very  intimate  connexion 
with  the  Cartesian  system: — these  things  do  not  settle  the  question. 
And  to  urge  either  his  occasional  sharp  criticisms  of  Descartes,  or  the 
bitter  repudiation  of  him  by  the  orthodox  Cartesian  schools,  as  a 
reason  for  refusing  to  regard  him  as  the  man  of  thought  who  revealed 
the  ultimate  meaning  of  the  Cartesian  categories  and  the  Cartesian 
method,  is  to  miss  the  genuine  core  of  the  situation  because  of  some 
of  its  external  incidents : — is  to  miss  the  main  set  of  the  tide  because 
of  one  or  two  of  its  prominent  and  rather  noisy  eddies.  Spinoza 
lived,  whether  he  would  or  no,  in  the  Cartesian  current.  In  his  long 
and  quiet  meditations,  the  Cartesian,  thought  ripened  and  worked 
itself  out.  And  the  outcome  was  that  he  became  to  the  first  stage  of 
modern  philosophy  what  Parmenides  had  been  to  the  first  stage  of 
Greek  philosophy — the  man  who  made  clear  the  goal  toward  which 
its  method  led,  and  the  view  of  the  world  which  lay  implicit  in  its 
working  principle. 

The  position  into  which  Spinoza  was  thus  brought  is  what  we 
have  now  to  consider.  The  advance  which  he  made  upon  the  Cartesian 
position  may  be  briefly  outlined  as  follows : 

In  the  first  place  he  saw  that  there  was  really  no  need  at  all  for 
Descartes  to  set  up  his  hopeless  problem  of  the  connexion  of  two 

i  E.g.,  Eth.  beginning  of  Pt.  III.  and  especially  beginning  of  Pt.  V. 
159 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

substances  which  are  independent  of  each  other.  For  what  Descartes 
had  on  the  one  side  was  really  nothing  more  than  an  attribute  and  its 
modifications.  And  what  he  had  on  the  other  side  was  likewise  really 
nothing  more  than  an  attribute'  and  its  modifications.  There  was  no 
need  at  all  to  put  a  distinct  substance  behind  each  of  these  attributes. 
Indeed  to  do  so  was  to  misuse  the  category  of  substance  itself.  For  a 
substance  is  precisely  that  which  is  needed  as  the  support  or  the 
home  of  a  variety  of  attributes;  it  is  the  single  substrate  required  to 
bring  the  many  attributes  back  into  unity  of  existence.  What 
Descartes  should  have  said,  then,  was  very  simple:  there  is  one  sub 
stance,  and  in  that  one  substance  both  these  attributes  inhere. 

So  that  Spinoza's  assertion  that  substance  is  One,  simply  com 
pletes  the  evolution  of  Descartes'  thought.  To  Descartes  substance  is 
that  "  which  so  exists  as  to  stand  in  need  of  nothing  beyond  itself  in 
order  to  its  existence."  But  upon  that  definition— unless  we  assert  the 
existence  of  a  plurality  of  absolutely  independent  universes  or  monads 
• — there  can  be  but  one  substance.  And  this,  as  was  noted  above, 
Descartes  himself  saw.  There  can  be  conceived,  he  admitted,  but 
one  substance  which  is  absolutely  independent  [i.e.,  which  really  does 
fulfil  the  definition],  and  that  is  God.  We  perceive  that  all  other 
things  can  exist  only  through  the  concourse  of  God  [i.e.,  according 
to  the  definition  are  not  substances  at  all] .  But  he  avoided  the  force 
of  this,  and  avoided  the  transformation  of  his  system  which  it 
required,  by  adding  that  the  term  substance  does  not  apply  to  God 
and  the  creatures  univoce;  "  that  is,  no  signification  of  this  word  can 
be  distinctly  understood  which  is  common  to  God  and  them."1 
Descartes,  that  is  to  say,  at  once  retains  and  does  not  retain  the  scheme 
of  the  world  which  he  had  worked  out  by  the  use  of  the  category  of 
substance.  But  the  excommunicated  Jew  with  his  piercing  intelli 
gence  could  not  remain,  as  the  loyal  (and,  let  me  insist,  sincere)  son 
of  the  church  remained,  in  such  a  position.  That  which  Descartes 
admitted,  Spinoza  insisted  upon,  and  put  in  its  proper  place  in  the 
system.  For  him,  from  the  beginning,  reality  is  One  Substance.  And 
this  is  the  first  great  step,  the  first  main  position,  in  Spinoza's  meta- 
physic. 

1  See  Principles,  I.  51. 
160 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

This  first  step  consisted,  it  will  be  seen,  in  a  stricter  use  of  the 
fundamental  Cartesian  category,  not  in  an  advance  from  it  to  a 
higher  category.  In  other  words,  Spinoza  did  not  correct  Descartes 
by  insisting  upon  a  more  accurate  treatment  of  the  cogito.  He  did 
not  point  out  that  the  objective  consciousness — that  of  which  the 
consciousness  of  extended  objects  is  one  aspect — is  correlative  to  the 
subjective  consciousness.  He  did  not  point  out,  to  put  the  same 
thing  in  another  way,  that  extension  is  relative  to  thought,  exists  for 
thought,  and  so  comes  within  the  sphere  of  thought.  Such  a  correc 
tion  as  that,  it  was  left  for  Kant  to  make.  What  Spinoza  did  was  to 
take  his  stand  upon  the  Cartesian  category  and  insist  upon  a  more 
thoroughgoing  application  of  it.  And  this  fact  is  of  the  very  highest 
importance  for  Spinoza's  whole  system.  For  it  not  only  gave  the 
first  step  in  it;  but  it  also,  as  we  have  now  to  see,  determined  the 
second  step.  And  this  second  step  was,  if  possible,  more  important 
than  the  first;  leads  directly,  indeed,  to  the  negative  conclusion;  or 
rather,  is  the  negative  conclusion. 

What  that  second  step  was,  an  illustration  will  help  to  make  plain. 
I  assert,  let  us  say,  that  self-consciousness  is  the  highest  principle  of 
science — that  reality  consists  in  a  single  self-conscious  and  self- 
determining  spirit,  and  in  its  activities  which  are  the  world  and  the 
history  of  the  world.  Thereupon  an  objector  challenges  me.  "  Self- 
consciousness  the  highest  principle  of  science  ?  But  exactly  what  does 
that  tell  me?  What  do  I  know  of  the  nature  of  self-consciousness?" 
But  to  this  I  can  at  once  make  an  answer :  Tat  tvam  asi — thou  art 
it.  Now  it  is  just  this  question  which  Spinoza  had  to  face  as  soon  as 
he  had  taken  that  first  step  which  we  have  just  seen.  Eeality  is  One 
Substance.  Be  it  so ;  but  what  does  that  tell  us  ?  What  can  we  know 
about  the  nature  of  the  One  Substance? 

And  the  key  to  this  situation  lay  in  the  fact  already  indicated; 
the  fact,  namely,  that  the  category  of  substance  itself,  by  which 
Spinoza  had  shown  himself  so  determined  to  abide,  involves  an  answer 
to  this  question.  This  Parmenides  had  seen,  and  had  worked  out 
with  clear  and  unflinching  logic.  This  also  Spinoza  saw  and  worked 
out;  and,  by  doing  so,  gained  the  great  regulative  principle  of  his 
philosophy. 

12  161 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

This  point  we  must  consider  very  carefully.  We  shall  best  com 
prehend  Spinoza's  procedure  here  by  comparing  it  with  that  of  the 
earlier  historical  instances  which  we  have  studied.  We  have  seen 
that  the  thinking  which  moves  on  the  level  of  the  categories  of  Being 
has  to  make  an  absolute  disjunction  of  "  is  "  and  "  is  not."  The  "  is  " 
is  a  pure  "  is,"  and  there  is  no  place  for  any  "  is  not "  in  it.  But 
from  this  two  things  at  once  follow.  First,  the  true  and  veritable 
Being  is  apart  from  all  change ;  for  no  "  is  not "  can  ever  creep  in  to 
bring  about  any  alteration.  Secondly,  that  true  and  veritable  Being 
must  be  apart  from  all  limitations  or  determinations;  for  these  also 
involve  an  element  of  "  is  not."  This  Parmenides  saw  and  his  whole 
system  was  simply  the  formulation  of  this  single  insight.  This,  too, 
the  mediaeval  Mystics  saw;  as  is  specially  evident  in  their  doctrine  of 
the  creature.  That  procession  from  God  by  which  the  creature  comes 
to  be,  is,  they  said,  a  procession  of  that  which  is  not  God,  i.e.,  is  a 
procession  of  non-Being.  Which  is  just  to  say  that  Being  belongs  to 
God  alone,  and  that  the  determinations  which  make  the  creature 
seem  to  be  an  individual  distinct  from  God,  are  really  nothing  at  all.1 

It  is  this  very  same  line  of  thought  which  Spinoza  at  this  point 
follows  out.  First  of  all  he  sees  that  determination  involves  an  ele 
ment  of  "  is  not."  But  this  insight  has  at  least  two  possible  mean 
ings.  To  a  man  who  stands  at  a  certain  logical  level,  it  has  one 
significance.  To  a  man  who  stands  at  a  certain  other  logical  level,  it 
has  an  altogether  different  significance.  It  will  be  advisable,  in  order 
to  understand  exactly  what  it  meant  for  Spinoza,  to  set  these  two 
meanings  side  by  side. 

The  first  is  expressed  more  exactly  by  saying  that  affirmation 
involves  negation.  Affirmation  and  negation  are  correlative.  Each, 
for  its  own  existence,  requires  the  other.  If  you  characterize  any 
thing  as  "  this  "  you  distinguish  it  from  "  that."  But — and  this  is 
the  key  to  the  whole  matter — it  is  just  because  a  thing  can  be  such 
a  "  this  "  that  it  can  have  a  place  and  a  function  in  the  system  of  the 
universe  at  all.  So  that  there  is  a  sense  in  which  determination  is 
negation.  But  this  insight  receives  all  its  meaning  from  the  still 

i  A  conclusion  to  which,  as  we  have  seen,  the  Vedantists  also  come ;  and  by  an 
argument  that  differs  more  in -mode  of  expression  than  in  logical  content. 

162 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

deeper  insight  which  goes  along  with  it.  For  the  universe  is  seen  to 
be  a  determinate  system — a  system  articulated  in  inner  determina 
tions;  and  the  kind  of  negation  involved  in  determination  is  seen  to 
be  necessary  to  the  existence  of  a  universe  at  all. 

But  that  is  not  what  the  principle  meant  to  Spinoza.  His 
thought  moves  in  the  region  of  the  Being-categories.  And  there  the 
"  is  not/'  so  far  from  being  considered  necessary  to  reality,  has  to  be 
cast  out  of  reality  altogether.  A  spatial  illustration  may  make  this 
somewhat  more  clear.  Imagine  a  cubic  foot  of  space  in  some  definite 
position — say,  at  your  right  hand.  Now,  what  is  it  that  prevents 
you,  considered  as  the  possessor  of  that  defined  portion  of  space,  from 
having  the  whole  of  space  ?  It  is  the  determinations — the  limitations 
which  give  to  that  piece  or  fragment  of  space  its  size  and  shape.  If 
these  particular  limitations,  and  all  limitations  of  this  kind,  were 
annihilated,  you  would  have  the  whole  of  space.  If  we  carry  through 
an  argument  of  this  sort,  not  with  regard  to  space  merely,  but  with 
regard  to  reality  as  a  whole,  we  get  Spinoza's  own  conception  of  the 
meaning  of  his  great  principle.  This  or  that  particular  thing — so  he 
felt — is  a  piece  or  fragment  of  reality.  But  if  all  the  limitations,  all 
the  determinations,  which  make  it  "  this "  or  "  that,"  were  swept 
away,  then  you  would  have  not  a  piece  or  fragment  of  reality,  but 
reality  itself.  A  particular  thing  is  the  One  Substance  with  the 
greater  part — in  most  cases,  indeed,  with  nearly  all — of  its  reality 
negated  by  determinations.1  Such,  then,  was  to  Spinoza  the  principle, 
Omnis  determinatio  est  negatio.  And  such  a  principle,  so  construed, 
leads  him  at  once  to  the  principle  that  the  One  Substance  is  indeter 
minate.2  Every  determination  is  viewed  as  a  negation  of  reality. 
Therefore  the  One  Eeality  is  beyond  all  determinations. 

1  See,  for  instance,  his  explanation  in  a  letter  to  Jarig  Jellis  (Ep.L.),  of  the  doctrine  that 
figure  is  negation.    "This  determination  [figxire]   therefore  does  not  appertain  to  the 
thing  according  to  its  being,  but  on  the  contrary  is  its  non-being."    (Elwes,  vol.  II.,  pp.  369, 
370.)    So  that  the  application  of  the  term  modus  to  particular  things  is  literally  consistent. 
A  particular  thing  is  a  mode  or  manner  in  which  the  One  Substance  exists.    And  it  is 
precisely  the  determinations  which  bring  it  about  that,  in  the  particular  thing,  the  One 
Reality  exists,  not  in  its  wholeness,  but  only  in  this  very  partial  mode  or  manner.    The 
full  carrying  out  of  this  would  have  given  the  Mystics'  doctrine  of  the  creature,  or  the 
Vedantists'  doctrine  of  the  human  self. 

2  See, for  example,  the  second  letter  to  Huyghens  (Ep.  XXXVI.)— "Now  since  the 
nature  of  God  is  not  confined  to  a  certain  sphere  of  being,  but  exists  in  being,  which  is 
absolutely  indeterminate,  so  His  nature  also  demands  everything   which  perfectly  ex 
presses  being ;  otherwise  His  nature  would  be  determinate  and  deficient."— (Elwes,  vol. 
II.,  p.  357-italics  mine.) 

163 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

So  far,  then,  Spinoza  has  done  exactly  what  Vedantist  and  Eleatic 
and  Mystic  did.  He  has  worked,  as  they  did,  with  a  category  which 
belongs  to  the  general  family  of  the  Being-Categories.  He  has  taken, 
as  they  did,  three  great  steps  which  represent  the  strictest  and  most 
faithful  working  out  of  the  logic  of  that  category.  First,  he  has  con 
ceived  reality  as  a  One — a  One  whose  unity  excludes  all  dividedness  or 
multiplicity.  Secondly,  he  has  affirmed  that  all  determinations  are 
negations  of  reality.  Thirdly,  he  has  declared  the  One  to  be  therefore 
indeterminate. 

These  principles  can  serve,  and,  as  we  already  know,  several  times 
have  served,  as  the  ground-lines  of  a  system  of  philosophy.  They 
are  not  merely  consistent  with  one  another,  but  are  a  rigidly  consist 
ent  development  of  the  inner  meaning  of  that  category  which  fur 
nishes  the  original  point  of  departure.  They  need  only  to  be  more 
minutely  explicated,  and  to  be  applied  to  the  problems  of  practice,  in 
order  to  give  such  a  full-orbed  and  thoroughgoing  system  as  is  found 
in  the  Vedanta  or  in  the  school  of  Eckhart.  In  dealing  with  Spinoza, 
then,  let  us  set  these  three  great  positions  together,  as  representing  a 
single  factor  or  movement  in  his  thought.  And  this  movement  in,  or 
aspect  of,  his  thinking,  let  us  call  his  "  first  metaphysic." 

But  now,  will  Spinoza  give  to  these  principles  just  that  develop 
ment  and  application  which  would  round  them  out  into  such  a  system 
as  we  have  seen  in  Yedantist  and  Mystic  ?  Our  study  of  those  earlier 
systems  has  shown  us  what  direction  such  development  and  applica 
tion  would  have  to  take.  There  remain  yet  a  fourth  and  a  fifth  step. 
The  fourth  step  would  proceed  as  follows. — All  determinations  are 
negations  of  reality.  Therefore  the  separateness  from  the  One  which 
the  particular  things  and  beings  of  the  world  appear  to  have  by 
reason  of  their  determinations,  is,  after  all,  an  illusory  separateness. 
The  One  alone  is,  and  what  distinguishes  us  from  it  is  really  nothing 
at  all.1  This,  when  fully  articulated,  would  give  us  a  doctrine  like 
the  Yedantist  doctrine  of  the  self,  or  the  Mystic  doctrine  of  the 
creature.  Then  the  fifth  step  would  advance  to  the  ethical  and 
religious  application  of  all  this — similar,  for  instance,  to  what  we 

i  Indeed,  with  regard  to  one  order  of  determinations,  Spinoza  did  virtually  affirm  this. 
In  the  letter  to  Jarig  Jellis  referred  to  above  (p.  163,  note)  he  called  the  determination  of 
figure  "  the  non-being  of  the  thing." 

164 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

have  already  seen  in  the  teaching  of  Eckhart  or  in  the  more  con 
sistent  teaching  of  the  "  Forest  Schools."  With  this,  the  system  as 
a  system  would  be  fully  rounded  out.  The  only  thing  that  would 
still  remain  to  be  constructed  would  be  its  Apologetic — its  defence  of 
itself  against  that  great  theoretical  objection  which,  as  we  have  seen, 
always  troubles  systems  of  this  kind. 


VI. 

"Will  Spinoza  round  out  those  three  principles  into  a  com 
plete  system  of  negative  philosophy?"  The  answer  is,  that  he  did 
not.  And  that  sets  us  two  problems.  First,  why  did  he  not? 
Secondly,  what  did  he  do  instead? 

Why  he  did  not  is  easy  to  see.  In  the  first  place,  as  we  have 
already  so  fully  seen,  in  a  philosophical  development  of  this  kind,  no 
sooner  do  you  reach  an  abstract  Absolute,  than  you  have  a  great 
theoretical  problem  on  your  hands.  The  finite  and  manifold  world 
comes  battering  at  your  gate.  And  with  this  problem,  in  one  form  or 
the  other,  you  must  deal.  For  if  you  say  that  the  finitude  and  mani- 
foldness  which  separate  us  from  the  One  are  really  nothing  at  all, 
and  that  therefore  we  really  are  not  separated  at  all,  are  not  really 
finite,  are  not  really  manifold;  then  the  answer  comes :  "  But  we  seem 
to  be  finite;  and  our  world  seems  to  be  manifold  and  subject  to 
change."  And  if  you  reply :  "  Yes,  but  that  seeming  is  an  illusion," 
then  you  are  still  in  difficulty.  For  at  once  the  question  arises :  "  In 
a  One  which  is  absolutely  without  division,  without  change,  without 
negation,  in  a  One  which  is  eternal  and  perfect,  how  has  such  an 
illusion  come  to  be?" 

Zeno,  indeed,  and  even  the  Vedantists,  could  cut  through  this  by 
an  easy  method — by  involving  the  objector  himself  in  self-contradic 
tions.  But  such  a  way  of  escape  was  not  in  accordance  with 
Spinoza's  temper.  And  moreover,  in  the  Europe  of  his  day,  there 
was  an  influence  at  work  which  gave  to  the  problem  now  in  question 
an  almost  overpowering  weight.  Since  the  Eenaissance  the  manifold 
world  had  been  taking  hold  on  men  as  never  before.  With  regard 
to  a  vast  variety  of  interests,  the  soul  of  man  had  been  kept  "  asleep  " 

165 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

for  no  small  number  of  centuries,  and  now  in  its  awakening    was 
intolerably  "  hungry."    For  one  thing,  men  were  turning  with  almost 
passionate  eagerness  to  the  study  of  the  physical    order  of  nature. 
And  their  devotion  to  such  inquiries  made  the  finite   world  seem  to 
them  an  ordered  and  veracious  thing,  whose  reality  was  not  lightly 
to  be  disputed.     It  should  be  noted,  too,  that  they  were    devoting 
themselves   particularly  to   those   mathematical   studies  upon  which 
any  scientific  conquest  of  nature  that  is  to  be  secure,  must  be  based. 
And  in  these  mathematical  and  physical  studies  certain  great  ways 
of  viewing  things  were  brought  very  decidedly  forward.    First,  there 
was  the  feeling  that  what  explained  the  world  was  present  in    the 
world.    Its  laws  and  causes  were  immanent  laws  and  causes.    In  your 
search  for  explanations  you  were  not  to  go  away  from  the  world   to 
something  outside  of  it  or  beyond  it.    Secondly,  there  was  a  growing 
sense  of  the  necessity  of  the  laws  operative  in  the  world — a  necessity 
conceived  at  first  mathematically  rather  than  mechanically  or  physi 
cally,  in  so  far  as  there  is  a  distinction  between  these  points  of  view.1 
It  was  not  merely  that  Spinoza  lived  in  an  age  which  was  resound 
ing  with  the  work  of  such  men.    It  was  not  merely  that  he  numbered 
such  men  among  his  friends  and  correspondents.2    It  was  not  merely 
that  his  mind  was  so  large  and  open  that  it  could  not   turn  a  dead 
surface  toward  any  great  intellectual  influence,  and  so  sincere  that 
it  could  not  lightly  dismiss  any  great  difficulty.     But  it  was  that  he 
himself,  in  a  very  true  sense,  was  one  of  these  men.     This  scientific 
tendency,  with  its  devotion  to  the  manifold  world,  with  its  view  of 
that  world  as  genuinely  real  and  the  home  of  eternal    laws   and 
inviolable  necessities — this  tendency  possessed  Spinoza's  soul  to  its 
very  core.    Not  that  it  made  him  a  physicist.    But  it  exercised  a  great 
influence  on  his  metaphysical  thinking.     In  a  word,  the  tendency 
which  once  had  been  great  in  the  world,  and  the  tendency  which  was 
now  coming  to  be  great  in  the  world — the  tendency  which  moves  away 
from  the  manifold  world  to  an  abstract  Absolute,  and  the  tendency 
which  sees  the  manifold  world  actuated  by  an  immanent  and  inviolable 

1  Cf.  Pfleiderer,  Philosophy  of  Religion  on  the  Basis  of  its  History  (Eng.  tr.  from  2nd 
German  ed.),  pp.  40,  41. 

2  E.g.,  Christian  Huyghens-or  even  Oldenburg. 

166 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

necessity— had  come  face  to  face ;  and  their  battleground  was  the  soul 
of  this  Jew.  But  in  that  calm  and  self-disciplined  mind  there  was 
no  outcry  or  tumult.  The  result  simply  was  that  by  the  side  of  that 
"first  metaphysic"  which  we  have  been  studying,  there  arose 
another.  This  we  may  call  Spinoza's  "second  metaphysic." 

The  leading  principles  and  the  inner  structure  of  this  second 
system,  it  must  now  be  our  task  very  briefly  to  study.  This  we  can 
most  conveniently  do  by  considering  two  chief  topics:  first,  the 
method  upon  which  Spinoza,  in  this  part  of  his  thinking,  worked; 
secondly,  the  "world-scheme"  built  up  by  the  use  of  that  method. 
And  in  dealing  with  the  latter  we  shall  have  to  discuss  the  relation  of 
this  "second  metaphysic"  to  the  "first  metaphysic";  for  Spinoza 
himself  regarded  his  thinking  as  a  single  system,  and  did  not  believe 
that  its  leading  factors  and  principles  fall  apart  into  two  or  three 
distinct  systems. 

The  significance  of  the  method  which  Spinoza  followed  in  this 
second  metaphysic  of  his  may  be  brought  to  clearer  light  by  a  com 
parison.  When  men  of  science  fling  themselves  upon  the  manifold 
world  of  our  experience,  in  the  endeavour  to  make  it  intelligible  as  a 
manifold,  the  process  which  they  carry  through  is  one  of  discovering 
unity  and  eternity  in  that  manifold.  That  the  facts  of  the  world 
change  on  our  hands,  that  they  are  one  thing  at  one  time  and  another 
thing  at  another  time,  is  precisely  what  makes  men  of  science  dissatis 
fied  and  sets  them  at  work ;  they  cannot  leave  facts,  and  the  successive 
changes  of  facts,  standing  isolated.  They  link  them  together  by 
searching  for — and  actually  discovering — those  permanent  and 
unchanging  relations,  the  formulations'  of  which  we  call  "laws  of 
nature."  And  in  this  labour  there  can  never  be  rest,  until  the  whole 
manifold  world  is  seen  as  a  single  system: — is  seen  as  a  unity  which 
is  also  an  eternity;  for  the  principles  which  mediate  the  unity,  and 
govern  all  the  manifoldness  and  change,  are  eternal  principles. 

But  to  say  this  is  to  say  that  the  method  of  scientific  men  is  a 
odos  avoo — a  "way  up."  They  begin  with  particulars,  opaque,  frag 
mentary,  evanescent,  altogether  unsatisfactory  to  the  intellect.  But 
from  these  they  climb  up  to  continually  wider  views  of  the  laws  which 
are  operating  in  them.  And  as  they  thus  go  up,  they  carry  the 


167 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

particulars  along  with  them ;  and  these  hecome  transformed — become, 
at  each  upward  step,  more  stable,  more  law-full,  more  satisfactory, 
in  every  way  to  the  intellect.  Then,  if  in  this  process  we  reach  a 
point  where  the  whole  system  of  existence  is  seen  as  transparently 
intelligible — is  seen  as  rational  through  and  through — we  can,  if  we 
wish,  turn  and  pursue  a  6&os  HCXTGO  •  We  can  come  down,  bringing 
our  highest  light  with  us,  and  illuminating  particular  spheres  of 
existence  with  it.  But — a  point  particularly  to  be  noted — we  can 
thus  "  come  down,"  only  because  we  had  first  laboured  through  the 
"  way  up."  For  precisely  the  value  of  that  "  highest  idea  "  to  which 
the  upward  way  led  us,  precisely  the  feature  of  it  which  makes  it 
possible  for  us  so  to  apply  it  as  we  "come  down,"  lies  in  this,  that 
as  we  worked  through  the  "  way  up  "  we  found  it  in  the  particulars, 
and  gradually  disentangled  it,  gradually  brought  it  out  into  a  light 
that  grew  clearer  as  we  went  higher.  Precisely  the  reason  that  we 
can  apply  the  highest  idea  as  we  "  come  down,"  is  that  it  is  not  some 
new  thing,  brought  down  from  above  and  alien  to  the  facts.  On  the 
contrary,  it  was  always  in  the  facts.  The  only  difference  is  that  in 
"coming  down"  one  is  applying  with  clear  and  easy  intelligence 
something  which  in  "  going  up  "  one  was  gaining  with  pain  and  trouble. 
The  "  way  up  "  is  what  nowadays  we  usually  call  the  "  synthetic 
method."  Eeally  it  is  a  method  of  combined  analysis  and  synthesis.1 
The  "way  down  "  on  the  other  hand  is  a  method  of  pure  analysis, 
made  possible  by  preceding  synthesis.  Historically,  however,  the 
analytic  method  has  frequently  attempted  to  stand  alone,  and  in  so 
doing  has  played  in  human  thought  a  great  but  not  altogether  a 
happy  part.  Standing  thus  alone,  it  is  cut  off  from  its  true  source 
and  support ;  its  conjunction  with  the  "  way  up  "  is  broken ;  and  then 
it  becomes  a  method  peculiarly  dangerous — all  the  more  dangerous, 
that  it  is  exceedingly  attractive  to  just  such  minds  as  Spinoza's.  In 
this  form,  it  starts  with  some  idea  as  a  premiss,  and  confines  itself 
strictly  to  the  task  of  getting  out  of  that  premiss  what  is  in  it.  All 
matter  not  contained  in  that  original  premiss  must  with  the  utmost 
severity  be  kept  out  of  the  conclusion.  And  if  any  such  matter  does 

i  There  are  people  who  take  a  perverse  pleasure  in  calling  it  "the  inductive  method." 
But  the  historical  English  use  of  the  term  "  induction  "  unfits  it  for  such  an  application. 

168 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

creep  in,  the  method  considers  itself  to  that  extent  to  have  failed. 
But  of  the  "  synthetic  method "  almost  the  opposite  is  true.  It  is 
precisely  the  mark  of  this  method  to  get  more  into  the  conclusion 
than  was  apparent  in  the  original  point  of  departure.  For  it  recog 
nises  that  its  proper  business  is  to  get  "  ideas  "  (or  categories)  and 
"facts"  properly  joined  together;  and  this  process  of  bringing  to 
facts  the  ideas  that  illuminate  them  and  that  draw  to  light  the  reason 
hidden  in  them,,  grows  continually  both  in  breadth  and  in  depth  as 
it  goes  on.  The  material  dealt  with  in  any  given  investigation  comes 
to  mean  more  and  more  as  the  investigation  goes  on.  The  original 
premisses  are  being  continually  "  reconstituted."  The  "  ideas "  get 
both  deeper  and  wider — increase  both  in  connotation  and  in  denota 
tion.  And  the  "  facts "  continually  take  on  wider  relations  and 
greater  significance.  With  the  "  analytic  method "  the  object  of 
investigation  remains  fixed,  fast,  .unchangeable  from  the  beginning. 
With  the  "  synthetic  method,"  the  more  you  deal  with  the  object  of 
investigation  the  larger  it  becomes  under  your  hands. 

The  analytic  method  in  that  strict  form  Spinoza  deliberately 
adopted.  About  the  question  of  method  he  had  thought  seriously,1 
and  in  the  treatise  De  Intellectus  Emendations  gives  us  his  conclu 
sion  on  the  subject — his  Organon.  The  treatise  may  be  described  as, 
among  other  things,  a  plea  for  the  use  of  the  "  way  down  "  without 
any  "  way  up " ;  at  least,  without  any  "  way  up "  in  the  sense 
described  above.  There  is  an  "  origin  and  source  of  the  whole  of 
nature,"  from  which,  as  one  may  put  it,  the  whole  process  of  nature 
flows  down.  And  if  we  are  to  have  a  "  faithful  image  of  nature," 
our  mind  must  have  a  highest  idea  which  represents  that  origin  and 
source,  and  then,  from  that  highest  idea,  must  deduce  the  whole 
descending  series  of  ideas  which  will  accurately  represent  to  us  the 
process  of  nature.2  Furthermore  Spinoza  thinks — or  rather,  he 
seems  to  take  for  granted — that  if  we  are  to  have  a  "  faithful  image 
of  nature,"  the  logical  movement  of  our  ideas  must  proceed  in  the 

1  See  Martineau,  Study  of  Spinoza  (1882),  p.  46  seq.     The  fact  (ibid.  pp.  48,  49)  that  the 
De  Intellectus  Emendatione',  which  originally  had  taken  the  lead  of  the  Ethics,  was 
gradually  dropped,  and  at  last  left  unfinished,  is  very  significant.    As  it  is,  the  treatise 
ends  with  a  problem  which,  upon  the  basis  there  laid  down,  is  impossible  of  solution. 

2  Elwes,  vol.  II.,  pp.  15, 16. 

169 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

same  direction  as  the  logical1  movement  of  nature.  Just  as  the  whole 
process  of  nature  flows  down  from  its  "  origin  and  source,"  so  must 
our  ideas  flow  down  from  the  highest  idea  which  represents  that 
"  source."  It  does  not  seem  to  him  permissible  that  our  mind  should 
reverse  the  order;  should,  in  attempting  to  form  a  "faithful  image 
of  nature/'  begin  with  the  lowest  particulars  and  run  backward  along 
the  course  of  their  outward  flow  from  their  "  origin,"  and  so  form  at 
last  a  "  highest  idea  "  corresponding  to  that  "  origin." 

This,  it  is  true,  at  once  raises  the  question :  "  But  how,  without 
such  a  otfds-  avco  as  has  been  described,  are  you  to  get  that  highest 
idea  at  all?"  And  Spinoza  actually  does  consider  this  difficulty 
under  one  of  its  specific  forms.  He  imagines  an  objector  to  say :  "  In 
order  to  be  certain  that  your  highest  idea  is  really  a  true  idea,  you 
will  need  a  proof.  But  that  will  call  for  a  still  higher  idea ;  in  fact, 
will  lead  to  an  infinite  regress  and  so  reduce  the  whole  situation  to 
absurdity."  Spinoza's  answer  to  the  mere  demand  for  "  proof "  is 
very  admirable.  But  he  does  not  see  the  deeper  question  which  is 
involved.  His  answer  comes  to  this :  "  Supposing  a  man  to  have 
gained  that  idea,  and  to  be  actually  usdng  it  in  the  victorious  ration 
alisation  of  nature — such  a  man  would  not  be  troubled  at  all  about 
your  miserable  question  of  proof."  "  Truth  would  make  itself  mani 
fest  and  all  things  would  flow,  as  it  were,  spontaneously  toward  him."2 
But  the  very  finality  of  his  answer  to  the  mere  brute  demand  for 
proof  apparently  blinds  Spinoza  to  the  fact  that  he  has  nowhere 
clearly  and  consciously  told  us  how  we  are  to  get  that  so  indispensable 
"  highest  idea." 

X  But  then,  how,  on  his  own  method,  is  he  to  construct  a  world- 
scheme?  If  he  is  to  do  so,  a  highest  idea  he  must  have.  And  since 
he  actually  has  done  so,  a  highest  idea  presumably  he  did  have.  The 
answer  is  that  he  did  have  a  highest  idea,  and  did  proceed  from  it  to 
the  elaboration  of  a  world-scheme.  But  the  way  in  which  he  got  at 
that  highest  idea  was  peculiar.  In  part  it  was  the  outcome  of  a  long 
course  of  reflection,  the  process  of  which  had,  so  to  speak,  died  away, 
leaving  the  conclusion  standing  out  like  a  self-evident  and  eternal 

J  !  For  with  Spinoza  the  movement  of  nature  is  a  logical  movement. 

2  Elwes,  vol.  II.,  p.  16. 
170 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

truth.  This  conclusion  he  formulates  into  a  certain  number  of 
definitions — two  or  three  of  which  contain  the  gist  of  the  whole 
matter — and  puts  these  at  the  head  of  his  world-scheme  just  as 
Euclid  put  his  axioms  at  the  beginning  of  his  book  on  geometry.  In 
part,  again,  the  highest  idea  was  got  by  taking  over  a  certain  concep 
tion  from  that  aspect  of  his  thinking  which  we  have  called  his  "  first 
metaphysic."  That  first  metaphysic  had  culminated  in  the  view 
that  reality  is  One  Substance.  And  with  One  Substance  the  "  second 
metaphysic  "  sets  out.  As  we  shall  see  more  fully  a  little  later,  these 
two  substances  appeared  to  Spinoza  to  be  one  and  the  same  thing, 
and  so  he  never  doubts  the  genuine  unity  of  his  own  thinking.  But 
really  the  two  are  radically  different  things.  The  transition  from  the 
first  to  the  second  metaphysic  is  not  the  logically  continuous  transi 
tion  from  one  part  of  a  unitary  system  to  the  next.  It  is,  on  the 
contrary,  a  transition  in  which  the  central  conception  undergoes  a 
most  subtle,  but  also  a  thoroughly  fundamental,  change.  The  one 
indeterminate  substance  becomes  the  One  Substance  with  infinite 
attributes.  What  blinded  Spinoza  to  the  greatness  of  this  change 
was  probably  the  fact  that  he  held  in  both  cases  to  his  great  regulative 
principle,  Omnis  determinatio  est  negatio — every  determination  (i.e.f 
ascription  of  determinate  limits,  of  definite  characters  and  qualities) 
is  a  negation  of  reality.  He  did  not  see  that  the  use  which  he  made 
of  this  principle  in  the  second  case  was  really  a  denial  of  the  principle 
itself. 

With  this,  then,  we  may  proceed  to  consider  the  ground-lines  of 
the  world-scheme  itself,  which  in  its  elaboration  constitutes  the  body 
of  his  "  second  metaphysic." 

The  first  point  which  we  have  to  consider  is  how  he  expresses  that 
highest  idea  which,  in  the  way  already  indicated,  he  puts  at  the  head 
of  his  philosophical  scheme  of  the  manifold  world.  First,  under  the 
names  causa  sui  and  substantia,  he  brings  forward  the  idea  of  a  being, 
unconditioned  and  self-existent — a  being  which  contains  within  itself 
the  ground  of  its  own  existence  and  the  ground  of  its  own  intelli 
gibility.1  Then,  under  the  name  God,  he  enriches  this  uncondi- 

1  Eth.  Pt.  I.  defs.  I.  and  III.  Erdmann  points  out  (Hist.  Philos.  Eng.  tr.  vol.  II.,  p.  59) 
that  the  expression  causa  sui  has  no  reference  to  a  process  of  self -creation,  but  means 
"  the  unconditioned." 

171 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

tioned  and  self-existent  being  with  infinite  attributes1 — an  attribute 
having  been  previously  defined  as  that  which  the  intellect  perceives 
as  constituting  the  essence  of  substance.2 

Then  from  this  starting-point,  he  goes  on  to  the  things  which 
are  not  self-referring  but  are  other-referring.  These — the  various 
individual  (i.e.,  particular)  things  and  beings  of  the  world — are 
viewed  as  modi;  that  is,  as  limited  "  manners  of  existence  "  of  the 
attributes  of  God.3 

Furthermore,  the  particular  way  in  which  God  expresses  himself 
in  modes  depends  absolutely  on  the  necessity  of  the  divine  nature. 
That  is  to  say,  the  system  of  particular  things,  the  order  of  the  mani 
fold  world,  is  an  order  of  the  strictest  necessity  and  most  inviolable 
law.  The  manifold  universe,  so  to  speak,  flows  down  from  the  one 
source  along  channels  absolutely  determined  by  the  nature  of  that 
source.4  In  a  teleological  system,  it  is  true,  there  is  also  necessity; 
for  the  end  is  the  supreme  law  of  that  whole  process  in  which  it  is 
being  realised.  But  in  such  a  system  as  that  now  before  us  there  is 
absolutely  no  place  for  teleology  or  for  the  teleological  kind  of 
necessity.5  The  strict  and  inviolable  necessity  of  this  system  is  a 
necessity  altogether  a  tergo. 

And  so  the  great  category  of  this  metaphysic  is  the  category  of 
cause.  But  we  shall  altogether  fail  to  understand  Spinoza  if  we  take 
his  continually  recurring  term  "cause"  in  the  sense  in  which  we 
ordinarily  use  the  term  "  efficient  cause/'  As  Erdmann  points  out,6 
Spinoza's  term  "cause"  means  mathematical  or  logical  cause.  His 
relation  of  "cause  and  effect"  is  our  relation  of  "ground  and  con 
sequent."  In  a  word,  the  universe  is  to  the  Spinoza  of  the  "second 
metaphysic,"  a  great  process  of  analytic  logic  in  which  the  nature 
of  God  is  the  original  premiss,  from  which  processes  of  endless 
"causation"  flow  forth. 

1  Eth.  Pt.  L,  def.  VI. 

2  Ibid.  def.  IV.— Mr.  Hale  White  translates:  "that  which  the  intellect  perceives  of 
substance,  as  if  constituting  its  essence." 

3  Eth.  I.  25.  Cor.  with  the  reference  to  prop.  15  and  def.  V. 

4  This  is  every  where  in  Spinoza;  but  see  especially  his  statement  of  the  necessity  of 
the  world's  procession  from  God,  in  a  letter  to  Hugo  Boxel  (Ep.  LIV). 

5  See  the  Appendix  to  Pt.  I.  of  the  Ethics. 

6  Hist.  Philos.  Eng.  tr.  vol.  II.,  p.  58. 

172 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

Such  is  the  skeleton  of  this  part  or  aspect  of  the  thought  of 
Spinoza.  His  amplification  of  it  into  a  detailed  system  is  exceed 
ingly  elaborate ;  and  to  one  who  simply  takes  his  stand  within  it,  and 
judges  it  by  its  own  standards,  offers  material  for  almost  endless 
question  and  criticism.  To  take  a  single  instance:  what  is  the  rela 
tion  of  the  One  Substance  to  the  Attributes?  The  definition  of 
"  attribute/'1  so  far  from  giving  us  a  clear  view,  may  itself  fairly  be 
called  a  nest  of  almost  hopeless  problems;  problems  which  centre  in 
the  question  of  the  place  ascribed  to  the  intellect  in  Spinoza's  scheme 
of  reality.2  But  from  all  these  questions  of  the  internal  criticism  of 
the  "  second  metaphysic  "  we  must  here  turn  away.  It  is  not  merely 
that  the  discussion  of  them  would  exceed,  a  score  of  times  over,  all 
possible  limits  of  space.  But  it  would  scarcely  be  in  line  with  the 
task  here  in  hand — that,  namely,  of  getting  at  the  main  lines,  the 
fundamental  movements  and  tendencies,  in  Spinoza's  thought,  and 
of  viewing  these  in  the  light  of  the  general  history  of  philosophy. 

Before  passing  on,  however,  one  thing  may  be  noted.  Graphic 
illustrations  of  rational  doctrines  are  usually  very  treacherous  helps. 
But  the  attempt  to  envisage  spatially  this  world-scheme  of  Spinoza's 
second  metaphysic  is  somewhat  useful.  Sir  Frederick  Pollock's 
illustration,3  supplemented  by  that  of  Professor  Erdmann,4  may  be 
used.  Let  us  imagine  an  infinite  number  of  infinite  plane  surfaces 
parallel  to  one  another  (the  attributes).  Each  of  these  is  ruled  with 
an  intricate  and '  continually  varying  pattern  made  up  of  geometrical 
figures  of  definite  shapes  (the  modes — particular  things  and  individ 
uals)  ;  and  the  number  of  figures  in  the  pattern  is  infinite  (infinite 
modes).  The  planes  are  different  from  one  another — let  us  say,  are 
of  different  colours.  But  the  pattern,  and  the  changes  that  keep 
taking  place  in  it,  are  identically  the  same  for  every  plane.  Let  it 
be  understood,  too,  that  if  you  ask  for  the  proximate  "  cause  "  of  any 

1  Eth.  I.  def.  IV. 

2  The  two  chief  interpretations  of  the  definition— which  involve  interpretations  of 
Spinoza's  whole  world -scheme— are  Erdmann's  and  Kuno  Fischer's.    More,  I  think,  can  be 
said  for  Erdmann's  than  is  nowadays  usually  taken  for   granted.      See,  however,  the 
exposition  of  Spinoza's  position  in  Joachim's  excellent  Study  of  the  Ethics  of  Spinoza 
(Clarendon  Press,  1901),  pp.  17-27. 

3  Spinoza,  his  Life  and  Philosophy,  2nd  ed.  (1899),  pp.  156,  157. 

4  Hist.  Philos.  Eng.  tr.  vol.  II.,  p.  62. 

173 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

one  of  those  geometrical  figures,  or  of  any  change  in  it,  the  answer  is 
to  be  given  by  referring  to  the  figures  around  it  and  to  their  changes. 
That  is  to  say,  God  is  the  source  or  "  cause  "  of  the  whole  system 
of  the  manifold  world — in  other  words,  that  whole  system,  viewed 
in  its  unity,  is  God ;  but  the  proximate  "  cause  "  of  any  particular 
thing  or  event  is  to  be  looked  for  in  the  other  particular  things  and 
events.  And  both  these  orders  of  causation  proceed  with  absolute 
necessity. 

It  remains  to  say  a  word  about  the  relation  to  each  other  of  these 
two  parts  or  aspects  of  Spinoza's  thinking  which  have  in  the  preced 
ing  pages  been  so  sharply  distinguished.  First,  let  it  be  distinctly 
understood  how  the  distinction  is  arrived  at.  As  a  critical  reader 
goes  through  Spinoza's  writings,  he  becomes  conscious  that  in  them 
there  are  distinct  tendencies,  distinct  points  of  view.  These  are  not 
set  apart  from  each  other;  nor  does  one  appear  later  than  another. 
On  the  contrary,  they  are  intertwined.  On  a  single  page,  even  in  a 
single  paragraph  or  sentence,  they  appear  together.  Spinoza  himself 
does  not  even  feel  that  there  is  such  a  distinction;  he  believes  that 
his  system  is  one  and  continuous.  Yet  there  is  such  a  distinction. 
Indeed  it  is  more  than  distinction.  It  is  contradiction.  The  appear 
ance  together  of  the  contradictory  views  and  tendencies  is  really 
only  juxtaposition,  only  external  union,  never  a  genuine  reconcilia 
tion.  And  what  has  here  been  attempted  is  to  bring  the  distinction 
and  contradiction  out  into  clear  consciousness,  by  disentangling  the 
tendencies  in  question,  formulating  them,  and  thus  setting  them,  in 
their  systematic  forms,  in  sharp  contrast  with  each  other. 

But  an  objector  may  urge :  when  all  this  is  done,  are  the  "  first 
metaphysic"  and  the  "second  metaphysic  "  really  so  different  from 
each  other?  Have  you  not  in  each  the  same  starting-point — unica 
substantia — and  the  same  great  regulative  principle — Omnis  deter- 
minatio  est  negatio?  So  that  Spinoza's  thought  is  one  continuous 
system  after  all.  The  answer  is,  that  the  regulative  principle  is  used 
so  differently  as  to  become  really  a  different  principle.  In  the  one 
case  it  requires  you  to  say  that  Substance  has  no  attributes  what 
ever.  In  the  other  it  leads  to  the  declaration  that  Substance  cannot 

174 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

have  a  limited  number  of  attributes,  nor  attributes  of  a  non-infinite 
kind.  And  with  this  the  Substance  itself  becomes  different.  The 
Substance  with  which  the  "  second  metaphysic  "  begins  is  not  truly 
the  Substance  with  which  the  " first  metaphysic"  ends. 

In  connexion  with  this,  however,  there  is  a  peculiar  Spinozistic 
doctrine  which  it  is  worth  our  while  to  notice.  Plotinus  had  to  face 
much  the  same  situation.  He  had  an  abstract  One.  And  he  also  had 
a  rational  cosmogony  and  cosmology.  But,  as  we  saw,  he  had  a  most 
ingenious  logical  principle  by  which  these  two  were  enabled  to  live 
together  in  peace.  "  It,"  he  said  of  the  One,  "  is  by  no  means  that 
of  which  it  is  the  principle."  The  powers  and  beings  of  the  manifold 
universe  are  altogether  dependent  upon  it.  But  it  goes  its  way  in 
the  most  absolute  independence  of  them,  and  so  retains  all  its 
characters — its  negative  characters — as  an  abstract  One.1  Now  there 
is  something  very  much  like  this  in  Spinoza.  "  An  effect,"  he  says, 
"  differs  from  its  cause  precisely  in  that  which  it  has  from  its 
cause."2  And  he  uses  this  principle  to  show  that  intellect  and  will, 
in  any  sense  in  which  men  use  these  attributes,  cannot  pertain  to 
God  who  is  the  sole  cause  of  all  things.  That  is  to  say,  he  uses  it 
for  the  very  same  purpose  which  Plotinus  had  served  by  the  principle 
noted  above;  he  uses  it  to  enable  the  abstract  One  to  be  the  source 
of  a  manifold  order  and  yet  remain  an  abstract  One.  It  is  an 
expedient  closely  akin  to  that  of  Plotinus;  so  closely  akin,  indeed, 
that  it  falls  under  the  same  condemnation.  It  is  subtle ;  it  is  ingeni 
ous;  but  it  forgets  the  implications  of  the  conception  itself  of 
relation.  You  cannot  have  a  relation  which  works  only  one  way; 
which  binds  B  to  A,  but  not  A  to  B. 


1  St.  Thomas  has  the  same  problem,  though  a  very  different  method  of  solving  it.    The 
Divine   nature    is    characterised  by    simplicitas.      Yet  in  God  is  a   multitudo     intel- 
lectorwn.    How  can  this  be?    St.  Thomas  answers  by  an  elaborate  doctrine  based  upon 
the  principle  that  the  Divine  nature  itself  is  God's  forma  intelligibilis ;  the  Divine  intel 
ligence  has  but  one  intelligible  form— its  own  nature  (v.  infra,  pp.  344,  345). 

2  Eth.  1. 17.  echol. 

175 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 


VII. 

So  far,  then,  for  this  aspect  of  Spinoza's  philosophy.  But  no 
sooner  have  we  seen  what  it  was,  than  we  are  once  more  face  to  face 
with  a  difficulty.  Just  as  in  the  metaphysical  views  expressed  by 
that  Spinoza  whose  spiritual  affinity  is  with  Eleatic  and  Vedantist 
and  Mystic,  there  was  a  great  theoretical  crux,  so  here,  in  the  meta 
physical  views  expressed  by  the  Spinoza  whose  spiritual  affinity  is 
with  the  Eenaissance  and  post-Kenaissance  men  of  science,  there  is  a 
great  theoretical  difficulty.  And  just  as  in  the  first  case  that  large 
and  open  and  sincere  mind  faces  the  difficulty  and  attempts  to  solve 
it,  so  here  does  he  face  it  and  attempt  to  solve  it. 

First,  let  us  see  what  the  present  difficulty  is.  It  may  be  stated  as 
follows. — On  the  one  hand,  in  that  way  of  viewing  the  world  with 
which  we  have  just  been  dealing,  particular  things  and  individual 
beings  all  stand  upon  a  level  and  all  are  actuated  from  behind. 
Spiritual  activities — the  energies  of  thought  and  will — stand  on  pre 
cisely  the  same  level  as  any  natural  activity.  Spinoza,  for  instance, 
expressly  affirms  that  will  does  not  appertain  to  the  nature  of  God 
more  than  any  other  natural  thing  does,  but  is  related  to  it  just  as 
motion  and  rest  and  all  other  things  are  related  to  it;  all  alike 
follow  from  the  necessity  of  the  divine  nature  and  are  determined  by 
it  to  exist  and  to  act  as  they  actually  do  exist  and  act.1  And  even  if 
Spinoza  did  not  expressly  declare  this,  it  would  still  follow  from  the 
general  point  of  view  which  he  here  holds.  From  natura  naturans — 
i.e.,  from  God,  the  substance  whose  essence  the  intellect  perceives  as 
consisting  in  infinite  attributes2 — follows  necessarily  natura  naturata, 
the  system  of  modes.3  And  in  natura  naturata  man  stands  on  a  level 
with  all  other  things,  and  man's  actions  on  a  level  with  all  other 
particular  events.  For  thought  is  one  attribute ;  extension  is  another ; 
and,  to  recur  to  the  illustration  mentioned  on  a  previous  page/  that 
total  pattern  which  appears  on  each  of  these  planes,  and  on  the 

i  Eth.  I.  32.  Cor.  2.  2  Eth.  I.  defs.  VI.  and  IV. 

3  Eth.  I.  29.  schol.  4  p.  173,  supra. 

176 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

infinite  number  of  other  planes,  flows  from  and  is  absolutely  deter 
mined  by  the  necessity  of  the  divine  nature.  To  give  a  precedence  to 
any  one  of  the  attributes,  or  to  break  down  their  absolute  independ 
ence  of  one  another,  their  absolute  separateness,  would  be  to  forget 
the  essential  principles  of  this  "  second  metaphysic." 

But  on  the  other  hand  there  is  something  which  compels  us  to 
do  just  those  things — to  give  a  precedence  to  one  of  the  "  attributes," 
and  to  break  down  their  separation.  What  this  is,  we  must  now  con 
sider. 

First,  as  we  have  already  seen,1  in  our  experience  subject  and 
object  are  correlative.  The  consciousness  of  objects  and  the  con 
sciousness  of  self  are  necessary  each  to  the  other;  if  either  be  taken 
away,  the  other  vanishes;  and  the  development  of  the  one  is  the 
development  of  the  other.  But  such  correlation  and  such  organic 
union  imply  community  of  nature;  imply  that  a  single  principle  is 
manifesting  itself  in  each  of  the  members  of  the  relation.  There 
is,  that  is  to  say,  community  of  nature  and  of  principle  between  the 
world  given  to  us  in  experience  and  the  self  that  knows  the  world 
and  acts  in  it  and  upon  it.  But  what  is  that  common  nature  of  the 
self  and  of  the  world  ?  This  question  we  could  answer  if  we  "  knew 
from  within  "  either  of  the  members  of  the  relation.  And  one  of 
them  we  do  know  from  within;  as  self-conscious,  we  know  by  inner 
awareness  the  nature  of  the  self.  So  that  precisely  in  the  self  lies 
the  key  to  the  nature  of  the  world.  That  principle  or  energy  of  which 
the  human  soul  is  an  inchoate  form — the  principle  frequently  in 
philosophy  called  "thought,"2  but  for  which  "spirit"  is  an  apter 
name — is  the  principle  of  the  whole  objective  order,  including  the 
order  of  extended  things  and  any  other  order  of  being  with  which 
man's  intelligence  can  enter  into  relation.  In  other  words,  the  unity 
of  the  world — the  world  in  the  greater  sense  of  the  term,  as  that 
system  of  things  in  which  the  human  soul  is  an  element — is  the  unity 
of  a  single  self-conscious  experience  in  which,  through  manifoldness 

1  Supra,  pp.  2,  3  ;  and  65.    Cf.  infra,  pp.  208,  209. 

2  In  the  sense  of  that  total   activity  in  which  psychologists  sometimes  distinguish 
"  feeling,"  "intellect,"  and  "will"  : — a  usage  of  the  term  "thought  "  which  is  convenient, 
and  dignified  by  long  custom,  but  open  to  misunderstanding. 

13  177 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

and  diversity,,  through  the  shock  of  conflict  and  the  discipline  of 
unfathomable  sorrows,  there  is  being  realised  an  ideal  end,  a  "  far-off 
divine  event/5 

— the  love 
Toward  which  all  being  solemnly  doth  move.1 

But  from  this  certain  consequences  follow  for  the  view  of  the 
world  expressed  in  Spinoza's  "  second  metaphysic."  First,  the  nature 
of  the  manifold  world  is  emphatically  not  the  nature  set  forth  by 
Spinoza  in  this  aspect  of  his  thinking.  The  process  which  is  the  life 
of  spirit  is  not  a  process  guided  by  a  necessity  that  acts  absolutely 
a  tergo.  On  the  contrary,  it  leads  itself  on  from  before.  It  presents 
ideal  ends  to  itself,  and  to  these  it  seeks  to  give  being  in  the  world  of 
achieved  realities.  True,  the  world,  as  a  spiritual  process,  has  neces 
sity  in  it.  But  it  is  the  necessity  which  arises  out  of  the  fact  that  the 
ideal  end  is  itself  the  supreme  law  of  that  process  of  development  of 
which  it  is  the  culmination  and  fulness.  And  since  the  source  alike  of 
that  end  and  of  that  necessity  communicates  its  own  nature  to  men, 
men  are  able  to  adopt  that  necessity  as  the  law  in  which  their  own 
being  finds  its  fulfilment.  So  that,  on  the  view  ultimately  given  by 
this  tendency,  necessity  itself  is  enlisted  as  a  good  soldier  "  under  the 
banner  of  the  free  spirit."2 

But  secondly,  this  same  process — the  life  of  spirit,  or,  as   Spinoza 

1  Arthur  Henry  Hallam,  Sonnet  On  the  Picture  of  the  Three  fates  in  the  Palazzo 
Pitti  at  Florence. 

2  Coleridge,  in  his  marginal  annotations  in  Crabb  Robinson's  copy  of  Spinoza,  has  an 
interesting  reference  to  Spinoza's  doctrine  of   necessity,  in  which  he  does  justice  to 
Spinoza's  distinctions  of  immanent  necessity  from  external  compulsion.     Commenting 
upon  Eth.  I.  28.  he  says :  "    .    .    .    It  is  true  he  contends  for  Necessity ;  but  then  he  makes 
two  disparate  classes  of   Necessity,  the  one  identical  with  Liberty,    .    .    .    the  other, 
Compulsion  =  Slavery.    If  Necessity  and  Freedom  are  not  different  points  of  view  of  the 
same  thing ;  the  one  the  Form,  the  other  the  Substance,  farewell  to  all  Philosophy  and  to 
all  Ethics.    It  is  easy  to  see  that  Freedom  without  Necessity  would  preclude  all  Science, 
and  as  easy  to  see  that  Necessity  without  Freedom  would  subvert  all  morals ;  but  though 
not  so  obvious  it  is  yet  equally  true  that  the  latter  would  deprive  science  of  its  main 
Spring,  its  last  ground  and  impulse  ;  and  that  the  Former  would  bewilder  and  atheize  all 
morality.    But  never  has  a  great  man  been  so  hardly  and  inequitably  treated  by  Posterity 
as  Spinoza.    ..." 

My  attention  was  called  to  Crabb  Robinson's  copy  of  Spinoza  (and  to  Mr.  Hale  White's 
publication  of  Coleridge's  annotations,  in  the  Athenceum,  No.  3630,  May  22, 1897)  through 
a  charming  act  of  kindness  on  the  part  of  Miss  Lucy  Toulmin  Smith  to  a  stranger  who 
one  day  entered  as  a  visitor  the  Library  of  Manchester  College. 

178 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

calls  it,  the  "  attribute  "  thought— cannot  be  placed  as  Spinoza  places 
it,  simply  on  a  level  with  the  other  aspects  of  reality  like  extension. 
Men  cannot  be  viewed  as  standing  on  a  level  with  "  all  other  natural 
things  " — as  having  merely  the  same  relation  to  the  ultimate  unity 
that  "motion  and  rest"  have.  On  the  contrary,  the  unity  of  exist 
ence  lies  in  the  fact  that  the  world  is  constituted  by  an  eternal  spirit; 
and  we  men  have,  as  the  essence  of  our  being,  a  nature  and  an  activity 
which  are  our  own  and  yet  are  His  nature  and  activity  communicated 
to  us.  We  are,  so  to  speak,  lesser  centres  in  that  system  of  which  He 
is  the  supreme  centre.  He  is  in  us,  and  we  live  in  His  life.  Through 
us,  or  rather  in  us  and  our  experience,  He  is  realising  an  eternal 
purpose;  and  we,  in  that  loyalty  to  domestic  and  social  and  civic 
duties  which  is  the  indispensable  basis  and  content  of  all  goodness, 
but  which  has  not  become  fully  itself  until  it  has  risen  to  the  form 
of  the  conscious  love  of  God,  can  adopt  that  purpose  of  His  as  our 
purpose,  and  thus  enter  more  and  more  upon  the  fulfilment  of  our 
vocation  as  sharers  in  the  divine  nature  and  the  divine  life. 

So  that  thought  itself  bears  witness  against  the  place  which  Spinoza 
has  assigned  to  it  in  the  world-scheme  of  his  "  second  metaphysic." 
And  this  witness  is  borne  by  all  the  phases  and  aspects  of  that 
thought  which  is  our  experience.  It  is  involved  in  the  possibility  of 
knowledge.  It  is  involved  in  ordinary  or  "  individual  "  morality.  It 
is  involved  in  those  great  structures  and  far-reaching  activities  which 
we  denote  by  such  terms  as  "  the  state  "  and  "  religion." 

Such,  then,  is  the  situation  which  the  Spinoza  of  the  "  second  meta 
physic  "  has  to  face.  What  will  he  do  ?  One  thing,  it  is  evident,  we 
must  not  expect.  We  must  not  expect  him  to  enter  upon  the  reflective 
mastery  of  the  whole  situation  by  grasping,  the  insight  just  noted,  and 
explicating  it  into  a  system  of  metaphysic.  That  was  left  for  the  men 
of  a  later  day ;  Spinoza  must  bring  Cartesianism  to  its  goal  before  the 
new  era  could  begin.  Descartes  had  broken  the  cogito  into  two,  and  it 
was  but  natural  that  Spinoza  should  harden  the  division.1  To  see  the 

i  This  is  one  of  the  chief  points  upon  which  Coleridge  fastened,  in  the  annotations 
referred  to  above  (p.  178,  note).  "  Spinoza  begins,"  says  Coleridge,  "  with  the  Phantom  of 
a  Thing  in  itself,  i.e.,  an  Object.  But  an  Object  implies  a  Subject  as  much  as  a  S.  an  O. ; 
therefore  that  only  can  have  a  chance  of  grounding  knowledge,  which  assumes  the  actual 
fact,  namely  X  =  Subject-Object  =  Object-Subject,  Ideal-real,  real-ideal!  the  Absolute- 

179 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA. 

cogito  restored  fully  to  its  rights  and  credited  with  the  whole  of  its 
own  possessions,  we  must  wait  for  Kant  and  Kant's  successors.  But 
still  a  certain  degree  of  advance  in  this  direction  was  possible  to 
Spinoza.  For  in  certain  of  the  aspects  or  manifestations  of  thought, 
the  witness  which  it  bears  to  itself  is  specially  emphatic.  Three  such 
aspects  may  be  noted  here ;  in  actual  experience  inseparably  intercon 
nected,  and  distinguished  here  only  for  convenience  of  statement. 
First,  there  is  morality  as  in  the  individual  man.  Secondly,  there  is 
the  morality  seen  in  the  ideals  and  regulative  principles  that  operate 
in  the  life  of  the  state.  Thirdly,  there  is  religion.  These — all  of 
them  works  of  thought,1  and  all  of  them  expressing  the  innermost 
nature  of  thought — stand  at  the  gate  of  any  philosophical  scheme  of 
reality,  demanding  admission  and  requiring  that  a  place  be  made  for 
them  which  they  can  occupy  without  laying  aside  their  essential 
characters.  This  demand  in  its  fulness  Spinoza  could  not  apprehend 
or  grant ;  to  do  so  would  have  been  to  effect  that  total  transformation 
of  the  philosophical  scheme  of  things,  which  became  possible  only 
after  Kant  and  the  Kantians  had  restored  the  cogito  to  its  rights. 
Something,  however,  Spinoza  could  do;  and  that  he  did.  It  was 
never  his  habit  to  close  his  great  intellect  against  any  demand  of 
scientific  sincerity.  He  listened  to  the  demand  now  in  question,  and 
did  the  best  he  could  to  meet  it.  The  result  was  that  he  advanced  to 
flashes  and  glimpses  of  insight,  and  occasionally  even  to  rather  fully 
articulated  doctrines,  which  represent,  or  imply,  a  view  of  reality 
different  from  either  of  the  two  which  we  have  so  far  seen  in  him. 
Keeping  to  the  expression  already  employed,  we  may  call  this  part  or 
aspect  of  his  thinking  his  "  third  metaphysic." 

The  relation  of  this  third  metaphysic  to  the  other  two,  it  will  be 
understood,  is  much  the  same  as  that  of  those  to  each  other.  In 
Spinoza's  thinking  they  are  intertwined.  They  appear  together  often 

eternally  foliating  the  Dual  [so  Coleridge  goes  on  in  his  attempt  at  a  speculative  doctrine  of 
the  Trinity]  as  this  the  Triad.  Being  +  the  Word  =  the  Spirit,  and  then  the  mystery  or 
Love  =  God  all  in  all  when  he  hath  finally  submitted  himself  to  whom  all  things  had  been 
submitted"  (from  the  annotation  of  Ep.  II.— Spinoza  to  Oldenburg).  Compare  with  this, 
a  sentence  from  the  comment  upon  the  reference  to  Nero's  crime  in  Spinoza's  third  letter 
to  Blyenbergh :  "  The  truth  is,  Spinoza,  in  common  with  all  the  metaphysicians  before  him 
v(Bdhmen  perhaps  excepted),  began  at  the  wrong  end— commencing  with  God  as  an  Object." 

i  In  that  greater  sense  of  the  word  already  noted  (=  rational  spirit). 

180 


THE    MBTAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

on  the  same  page,,  sometimes  even  in  the  same  sentence;  and  are 
never  observed  to  speak  hostile  words  to  one  another.  Yet  this  appar 
ently  so  close  union  is  only  external.  In  reality  they  are  citizens  not 
merely  of  different,  but  of  deeply  severed,  kingdoms;  to  genuine 
reconciliation  and  unity  they  never  come.  If  it  had  been  Spinoza's 
fate  to  occupy  a  position  similar  to  that  of  Socrates — to  stand  at  the 
head  of  a  great  philosophical  succession  which  included  in  itself  virtu 
ally  all  the  serious  and  disinterested  thinkers  of  the  age — we  should 
probably  have  found  in  that  succession  three  great  schools,  as  distinct 
from  one  another  as  were  those  which  alike  claimed  Socrates  as  their 
head. 

Let  us  consider,  then,  the  chief  discussions  and  doctrines  which 
constitute  this  "  third  metaphysic."  It  would  be  very  interesting  to 
study  those  occasional  phrases  scattered  through  his  writings, 
which  have  a  bearing  on  this.  For  instance,  in  the  very  first  sentence 
of  the  De  Intellectus  Emendatione  we  find  him  resolving  "  to  inquire 
whether  there  might  be  some  real  good  having  power  to  communicate 
itself."  A  few  pages  farther  over  we  find  him  mentioning  "  the  union 
existing  between  the  mind  and  the  whole  of  nature."  In  the  mouth 
of  a  Kantian — or  of  a  Platonist — such  conceptions  would  have  an 
immeasurable,  a  world-penetrating,  significance.  But  we  should  go 
astray  if  we  supposed  that  they  had  so  great  a  meaning  for  Spinoza. 
We  shall  be  on  safer  ground  if  we  turn  at  once  to  his  discussion  of 
those  three  great  works  or  expressions  of  thought,  in  which  the  inner 
nature  of  thought  simply  forces  itself  on  the  attention  of  the  observer ; 
to  his  discussion,  namely,  of  in^iyj^ual,.jaoialiiy,  of  the  state,  of 
religion. 

His  elaborate  discussion  of  the  first  of  these  cannot  be  reproduced 
within  the  limits  of  these  pages.  Nor  is  it  necessary  that  it  should. 
For  it  is  only  with  the  ground-lines  of  the  discussion,  only  with  its 
controlling  conceptions,  that  we  are  specially  concerned. 

These  amount  to  a  virtual  bringing  back  of  that  ideal  point  of 
view,  and  of  those  teleological  categories,  which  in  the  "  second  meta- 
physic  "  had  been  driven  into  extremest  exile.  This  we  may  see  by 
considering  the  three  main  topics  of  the  discussion:1  first,  the  con- 

i  Topics  which  are,  of  course,  most  closely  interconnected. 
181 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

ception  of  the  moral  good;  secondly,  the  doctrine  of  man's  freedom; 
thirdly,  the  discussion  of  the  way  of  attaining  to  that  freedom  and 
that  good. 

Under  the  first  of  these  three  topics  we  have  to  consider  in  especial 
two  great  conceptions  :  that  of  the  "  summum  ~bonum  " ;  and  that  of  the 
"  conatus  in  suo  esse  perseverandi."  You,  as  a  man,  have  a  given  esse 
or  nature,  and  it  is  your  summum  bonum  to  maintain — or  rather,  as 
we  shall  see  presently,  to  realise  and  fulfil — that  esse.  It  is  true  that 
the  mere  use  of  these  two  phrases  does  not  necessarily  introduce  a  new 
point  of  view.  For  the  summum  bonum  might  be  defined  to  consist 
simply  in  your  position  as  a  necessitated  mode  of  one  of  the  attributes ; 
and  the  esse,  likewise,  as  consisting  simply  in  the  nature  given  you  by 
that  position.  But  precisely  the  key  to  the  situation  is  that  that  is 
just  how  Spinoza  does  not  conceive  them.  The  esse  is  conceived,  not 
as  the  nature  given  you  by  your  mere  position  as  a  necessitated  mode 
in  the  great  "  causal "  series,  but  as  something  against  which  that 
position  wages  war  and  which  you  have  to  maintain  in  the  face  of 
that  position.  And  that  maintenance,  that  fulfilment  of  your  nature 
in  the  face  of  an  implacably  hostile  situation,  is  your  summum  bonum. 
This,  however,  we  must  consider  in  slightly  greater  detail.  First 
of  all,  in  man  a  great  dualism  of  reason  and  passion  is  affirmed.1  But, 
secondly,  while  the  one  side  of  this  represents  our  position  as  necessi 
tated  modes  in  the  great  causal  nexus  of  modes,  it  is  precisely  in  the 
other  side  that  our  summum  bonum  is  to  be  sought.  "  Inasmuch  as 
the  intellect  is  the  best  part  of  our  being/'  says  Spinoza  in  the  remark 
able  fourth  chapter  of  the  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,  "  it  is 
evident  that  we  should  make  every  effort  to  perfect  it  as  far  as  possible 
if  we  desire  to  search  for  what  is  really  profitable  to  us.  For  in  intel 
lectual  perfection  the  highest  good  should  consist/'  "  Since/'  he 
argues  in  the  Ethics,2  "  this  effort  of  the  mind  wherewith  the  mind 
endeavours,  in  so  far  as  it  reasons,  to  preserve  its  own  being,  is  nothing 
else  but  understanding;  this  effort  at  understanding  is  the  first  and 
single  basis  of  virtue,  nor  should  we  endeavour  to  understand  things 
-for  the  sake  of  any  ulterior  object  .  .  ."  "We  know  nothing/' 

i  Throughout  Pts.  IV.  and  V.  of  the  Ethics. 
2  IV.  26.  dem. 

182 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

runs  the  next  proposition,  "  to  be  certainly  good  or  evil,  save  such 
things  as  really  conduce  to  understanding  or  such  as  are  able  to  hinder 
us  from  understanding."  Again,  "  In  life  it  is  before  all  things  useful 
to  perfect  the  understanding,  or  reason,  as  far  as  we  can,  and  in  this 
alone  man's  highest  happiness  or  blessedness  consists  .  .  ."1  And 
since  the  good  lies  in  understanding,  it  follows  that  "  the  mind's 
highest  good  is  the  knowledge  of  God,  and  the  mind's  highest  virtue 
is  to  know  God/'2  So,  then,  in  this  dualism  of  reason  and  passion, 
the  good  lies  altogether  within  one  of  the  two  sides.  And  the  other 
side — the  side  which  wars  against  our  attaining  of  this  good,  and,  in 
so  far  as  it  prevails,  constitutes  our  "  bondage  " — is,  as  was  said  a 
moment  ago,  just  what  represents  our  place  as  modes  in  the  great 
nexus  of  modes.  For  the  passions  are  the  ways  in  which  external 
causes  act  upon  us.3  That  is  to  say,  they  represent  man  as  the  "  second 
metaphysic  "  must  represent  him  altogether ;  namely,  as  one  mode 
altogether  determined  by  the  "  causal "  activities  of  the  other  modes. 
Spinoza  states  both  sides  of  this  dualism  very  strongly.  The  "  bondage 
of  man  "  he  states  so  strongly — i.e.,  in  stating  it  he  clings  so  closely 
to  the  point  of  view  of  his  "  second  metaphysic  " — that  he  makes  it 
quite  hopeless.4  But  he  states  the  other  side  just  as  strongly.  And 
that  he  does  not  consider  the  bondage  hopeless  he  still  further  shows 
by  describing  the  way  in  which  man  is  to  deliver  himself  from  it,  and 
so  to  attain  his  good. 

This  brings  us  to  the  second  of  these  topics,  Spinoza's  view  of 
freedom,  which  is  really  nothing  other  than  his  conception  of  the 
Good  stated  from  a  special  point  of  view.  To  study  it  for  its  own 
sake  would  be  to  undertake  one  of  the  most  interesting  and  most 
instructive  tasks  in  the  history  of  philosophy.  But  here,  once  more, 
for  the  purpose  of  our  present  discussion  we  may  sum  up  the  matter  in 
a  sentence  or  two.  Spinoza  conceives  the  freedom  of  man  to  lie  pre 
cisely  in  man's  fulfilling  the  law  of  his  own  being  and  living  out  his 
own  true  nature,  unshackled  and  undisturbed  by  those  "  external 
causes"  to  which  reference  was  made  above.  But  we  have  just  seen  how 

i  Eth.  IV.  Appendix  (IV.). 

2  Eth.  IV.  28. 

3  See  Eth.  IV.  5.    Cf.  the  Corollary  of  the  preceding  proposition. 
*  In  Eth.  IV.,  take  the  Axiom  along  with  propositions  3,  4,  5,  6,  7. 

183 


THE   METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

Spinoza  conceives  that  true  nature  of  man  and  that  true  law  of  man's 
being.  He  conceives  them,  namely,  in  a  way  which  goes  far  beyond 
the  point  of  view  of  the  "  second  metaphysic,"  and  makes  no  slight 
advance  in  the  direction  of  restoring  to  the  cogito  its  true  meaning 
and  its  true  place  and  function  in  the  universe.1 

And,  as  we  might  expect,  we  find  the  same  tendency  in  Spinoza's 
discussion  of  the  third  of  these  topics — the  way  of  attaining  to 
freedom  and  the  Good.  We  need  not,  however,  dwell  long  upon  it. 
It  is  enough  to  say  that  Spinoza  shows  at  length  how  the  realm  of  the 
understanding  is  to  be  extended  over  the  realm  of  the  passions;2  in 
other  words,  how  we  men  are  to  break  away  from,  and  to  rise  above, 
the  position  to  which  we  would  be  absolutely  confined  if  we  were  really 
the  "  modes  "  which  the  "  second  metaphysic  "  holds  us  to  be.  Eeason, 
when  it  has  risen  through  the  ascending  stages  of  knowledge,3  comes 
to  that  union  with  God — that  union  with  "  the  whole  of  nature  " — in 
which  it  sees  all  things  under  the  aspect  of  eternity  and  necessity ;  and 
learns  to  accept  them,  because  when  thus  seen  they  are  seen  as  parts  of 
perfection.  But  it  accepts  them,  not  as  a  mere  mode  accepts  them — i.e., 
as  an  external  fate;  in  accepting  them,  it  acts  from  within  and  of  its 
own  accord ;  for  it  has  risen  to  the  point  of  view  of  the  eternal,  and 
so  accepts  them  not  only  as  good,  but  as  being  its  Good — that  in  which 
it  fulfils  its  nature.  And  this  state  of  the  soul — in  which  it  is  no 
longer  swayed  hither  and  thither  by  those  forces  from  without  which 
act  on  us  through  the  passions,  but  is  guided  solely  by  that  highest 
form  of  reason — is  freedom. 

So  much,  then,  for  the  question  how  far  Spinoza,  in  dealing  with 
individual  morality,  introduces  a  new  and  higher  point  of  view  into 
his  system.  Next  we  have  to  consider  the  same  question  with  regard 
to  his  treatment  of  the  state  and  of  religion. 

1  Spinoza's  conception  of  freedom,  in  its  elaborate  form,  is  of  course  to  be  looked  for  in 
the  latter  part  of  Eth.  IV.  and  in  Eth.  V.    But  it  comes  forward  in  many  passages  in  his 
writings— passages  often  remarkable  ;f  or  a  keenness  and  brilliancy  that  contrast  strik 
ingly  with  the  general  calm  of  his  pages.    See,  for  instance.  Tract.  TheoL-Pol.  cap.  IV. 
(Elwes,  vol.  I.,  pp.  58  and  66) ;  letter  to  Isaac  Orobio  (Ep.  XLIX.)  with  which  cf.  the  keen 
outburst  in  Eth.  V.  41,  schol. ;  and  especially  Tract.  Pol.,  II.  §  7,  and  the  letter  addressed  to 
Schaller  dealing  with  Tschirnhausen's  objections.    (Ep.  LVIII.) 

2  See  the  earlier  part  of  Eth.  V.—  specially  the  scholium  to  proposition  20. 

3  See  pp.  191, 192  infra. 

184 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

In  Spinoza's  discussion  of  individual  morality,  we  were  specially 
concerned  to  note  how  the  view  there  taken  by  him  lifted  men  above  the 
position  of  mere  modes  of  one  of  the  attributes.  So  far  as  this  went, 
it  constituted  a  recognition  alike  of  the  true  nature  of  the  cogito  and 
of  its  true  place  and  function  in  the  system  of  reality.  Now,  if  Spin 
oza  holds  to  the  new  point  of  view,  as  he  advances  from  the  individ 
ual  to  the  state,  this  recognition  will  be  made  both  deeper  and  wider. 
The  whole  insight,  so  to  speak,  will  move  in  a  wider  field,  and  thus 
the  process  of  restoring  the  cogito  to  its  rights  will  be  carried  onward 
toward  its  conclusion. 

For  the  state  is  one  of  the  great  works  of  the  cogito;  or,  to  employ 
more  modern  language,  it  is  a  great  structure  of  objective  reason. 
The  long  process  of  the  formation  of  the  state  is  one  in  which  the 
rational  spirit  has  struggled  and  still  is  struggling,  to  work  out  a  form 
of  organised  society  in  the  life  of  which  that  rational  spirit  will  find 
its  own  true  home,  will  fulfil  the  law  of  its  own  being,  will  realise  its 
own  essential  and  eternal  nature.  Hence,  the  state  is  not  something 
external  to  man.  Nor  do  its  laws  ultimately  represent  a  mere  com 
pulsion  from  without.  On  the  contrary,  it  is  only  by  living  the  life 
of  a  member  of  the  state  that  man  truly  becomes  man  at  all.  And 
his  political  freedom  consists  precisely  in  belonging  to  a  state  whose 
laws  are,  such  that  he  can  adopt  them  as  his  own  laws  and  find  in  them 
his  guide  toward  the  fulfilment  of  his  own  nature. 

Under  certain  limitations  this  view  of  the  state  was  taken  for 
granted  by  Greek  citizens ;  still  more  by  Greek  men  of  thought.  Freed 
from  the  Greek  limitations,  it  received  an  elaborate  and  systematic 
formulation  from  Hegel.  And  by  at  least  one  statesman  of  modern 
days  it  was  thrown  into  the  language  of  practical  politics — in  Burke' s 
great  saying  that  the  state  is  not  a  contract  limited  to  man's  lower 
interests,  but  on  the  contrary  is  "  a  partnership  in  all  science,  a  part 
nership  in  all  art,  a  partnership  in  every  virtue,  and  in  all 
perfection." 

But  Spinoza,  when  he  passes  from  the  consideration  of  individual 
morality  to  the  consideration  of  the  state,  does  rot  make  this  advance. 
And  the  reason  why  is  plain.  In  that  very  consideration  of  individual 
morality,  he  conceives  the  good,  as  we  have  just  seen,  in  a  thoroughly 

185 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

iutellectualistic  way.  Now,  an  intellectualistic  good  is  not  a  selfish 
good.  Nor  is  it  an  individualistic  good  in  the  sense  that  the  obtaining 
of  it  by  one  man  prevents  the  obtaining  of  it  by  others.  But  it  is 
individualistic  in  the  sense  that  it  can  be  realised  by  men  who  stand 
almost  alone;  who  live,  as  Spinoza  himself  did,  in  comparative 
solitude.  It  is  not  necessarily  a  good  the  very  striving  after  which 
leads  to,  and  is  fulfilled  in,  the  building  up  of  great  social  structures 
and  the  establishing  of  great  social  institutions. 

Moreover,  the  view  which  Spinoza  takes  of  the  whole  cogito  is  in 
accordance  with  that  intellectualistic  view  of  the  good.  When  the  will 
is  reduced  to  intellect;1  and  when,  in  the  peculiar  way  described  by 
him,  the  intellect  extends  its  domain  over  the  emotions  and  passions : — 
then  the  cogito  which  is  left  is  not  one  which  is  driven  forth  by  its 
own  nature  to  social  activities,  nor  one  which  can  find  its  true  home 
only  in  the  life  of  an  organised  society. 

Hence  in  Spinoza's  views  concerning  the  state  we  must  not  look 
for  any  great  advance  in  the  direction  indicated  above.  First,  indeed, 
we  shall  see  that  certain  of  his  political  positions  do  look  in  that 
direction.  But  we  shall  have  also  to  notice  that  in  his  latest  writing, 
the  Tractatus  Politicus,  a  theory  comes  forward  which  almost  super 
sedes  those  and  swings  far  backward  toward  the  point  of  view  of  the 
"  second  metaphysic." 

First,  then,  for  the  positions  which  imply  the  view  that  the  state 
stands  in  organic  relation  to  the  individual,  and  that  therefore  he  who 
would  be  truly  a  man  and  would  truly  realise  man's  nature,  must  live 
in  the  state  and  perform  the  functions  of  a  citizen. — These  are  found 
particularly  in  the  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus.  For  instance,  in 
the  fourth  chapter,2  he  refuses  to  regard  legislation  as  in  its  genuine 
nature  a  force  acting  on  the  citizen  from  without.  He  rises  to  one  of 
his  rare  invectives  when  he  speaks  of  those  whose  object  in  obeying 
law  is  merely  the  avoidance  of  punishment.  But  the  man  who 
follows  the  precept  suum  cuique,  not  because  he  fears  the  gallows,  but 
"  from  a  knowledge  of  the  true  reason  for  laws  and  their  necessity  " — 

1  See  Eth.  II.  49.  Cor.    Spinoza  here  says  that  the  will  and  the  intellect  are  one  and  the 
same  thing.    But,  with  him,  that  virtually  means  the  reduction  of  the  will  to  intellect. 

2  Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  58. 

186 


THE    MBTAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

he  it  is  who  "  acts  from  a  firm  purpose  and  of  his  own  accord,  and  is 
therefore  properly  called  just."  Again,  in  the  sixteenth  chapter,  in 
dealing  with  the  duty  of  subjects  to  obey  the  commands  of  the 
sovereign  power,  he  remarks :  "  That  state  is  the  freest  whose  laws 
are  founded  on  sound  reason,  so  that  every  member  of  it  may,  if  he 
will,  be  free ;  that  is,  live  with  full  consent  under  the  entire  guidance 
of  reason."1 

And  the  attitude  revealed  in  such  hints  as  those  is  carried  still 
farther  in  what  we  may  call  his  theory  of  the  relation  of  church  and 
state.  "  God,"  he  says,  "  has  no  special  kingdom  among  men,  except 
in  so  far  as  He  reigns  through  temporal  rulers."2  "  It  is  only 
through  "  those  who  possess  the  right  of  ruling  and  legislating  "  that 
God  rules  among  men,  and  directs  human  affairs  with  equity."3  Thus 
"secular  rulers  are  the  proper  interpreters  of  divine  right."4  But 
from  this  it  follows  that  the  sovereign  rulers  "  are  the  proper  inter 
preters  of  religion  and  piety."5  "  If  we  would  obey  God  rightly," 
"  the  outward  observances  of  religion  and  all  the  external  practices  of 
piety  should  be  brought  into  accordance  with  the  public  peace  and 
well-being."6  "  We  cannot,  therefore,  doubt  that  the  daily  sacred 
rites  .  .  .  are  under  the  sole  control  of  the  sovereign  power;  no 
one,  save  by  the  authority  or  concession  of  such  sovereign,  has  the 
right  or  power  of  administering  them,  of  choosing  others  to  adminis 
ter  them,  of  defining  or  strengthening  the  foundations  of  the  church 
and  her  doctrines;  of  judging  on  questions  of  morality  or,  acts  of 
piety;  of  receiving  any  one  into  the  church  or  excommunicating  him 
therefrom,  or,  lastly,  of  providing  for  the  poor."7  With  these  passages 
may  be  taken  one  of  wider  scope  from  the  last  chapter  of  the  treatise. — 
"  It  follows  plainly  from  the  explanation  given  above  of  the  founda 
tions  of  a  state,  that  the  ultimate  aim  of  government  is  not  to  rule  or 
restrain  by  fear,  nor  to  exact  obedience,  but  contrariwise  to  free  every 

i  Elwes,  vol.  L,  p.  206. 
2  Tract.  Theol.-Pol.  cap.  XIX.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  245. 

3  Loc.  cit.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  248. 

4  Loc.  cit.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  249. 

5  Loc.  cit.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  249. 

6  Loc.  cit.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  249. 

7  Loc.  cit.    Elwes,  vol.  L,  p.  252. 

187 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

man  from,  fear,  that  he  may  live  in  all  possible  security;  in  other 
words,  to  strengthen  his  natural  right  to  exist  and  work  without  injury 
to  himself  or  others.  No,  the  object  of  government  is  not  to  change 
men  from  rational  beings  into  beasts  or  puppets,  but  to  enable  them 
to  develop  their  minds  and  bodies  in  security  and  to  employ  their 
reason  unshackled;  neither  showing  hatred,  anger  or  deceit,  nor 
watched  with  the  eyes  of  jealousy  and  injustice.  In  fact,  the  true  aim 
of  government  is  liberty."1 

The  view  of  the  organic  relation  of  the  individual  and  the  state 
implies  not  only  a  doctrine  as  to  what  the  function  of  the  law  is  and 
as  to  why  we  should  obey  the  law.  It  implies  also  a  doctrine  concern 
ing  the  width  of  state  action :  whatever  the  state  can  do  to  enable  its 
individual  members  to  live  truly  human  lives  and  to  fulfil  the  nature 
of  man,  that  the  state  ought  to  do.  The  Spinozistic  views  just  noted 
lean  toward  a  doctrine  of  this  kind.  But  Spinoza  never  works  his  way 
to  a  clear  possession  of  it.  Alongside  such  passages  as  those  referred 
to  in  the  immediately  preceding  paragraphs,  stand  others  wherein 
Spinoza  regards  the  function  of  the  state  as  limited  to  the  securing  of 
peace,  and  the  guarding  of  the  individual  against  the  hindrances  of 
violence  and  disorder.  "  By  human  law,"  he  says  in  the  fourth  chapter 
of  the  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,2  "  I  mean  a  plan  of  living 
which  serves  only  to  render  life  and  the  state  secure."  And  in  the 
Tractatus  Politicus  he  says :  "  The  quality  of  the  state  of  any 
dominion  is  easily  perceived  from  the  end  of  the  civil  state,  which  end 
is  nothing  else  but  peace  and  security  of  life.  And  therefore,  that 
dominion  is  the  best  where  men  pass  their  lives  in  unity  and  the  laws 
are  kept  unbroken."3  Though  even  here  it  is  fair  to  note  the  qualifica 
tion  which  he  presently  adds  :4  "  When,  then,  we  call  that  dominion 
best,  where  men  pass  their  lives  in  unity,  I  understand  a  human  life, 
defined  not  by  mere  circulation  of  the  blood,  and  other  qualities 
common  to  all  animals,  but  above  all  by  reason,  the  true  excellence  and 
life  of  the  mind." 

i  Tract.  TheoL-PoL  cap.  XX.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  pp.  258,  259. 
2  Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  59. 

3  Tract.  Pol.  V.  §  2.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  313. 

4  Ibid.  cap.  V.  §  5.    Elwes.  vol.  I.,  p.  314. 

188 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

But  finally,  as  was  said  above,  we  come,  at  the  opening  of  the 
Tractatus  Politicus,  upon  a  doctrine  which  swings  decidedly  back 
toward  the  point  of  view  of  the  second  metaphysic.  This  is  the  great 
doctrine  that  natural  right  is  "  potentia  " ;  and  this  doctrine  roots 
itself  directly  in  the  view  that  man  is  "pars  naturae,"  i.e.,  in  the 
language  of  the  Ethics,  a  mode  of  one  of  the  attributes. 
"...  Every  natural  thing  has  by  nature  as  much  right  as  it 
has  power  to  exist  and  to  operate;  since  the  natural  power  of  every 
natural  thing  whereby  it  exists  and  operates,  is  nothing  else  but  the 
power  of  God  which  is  absolutely  free.  And  so  by  natural  right  I 
understand  the  very  laws  or  rules  of  nature,  in  accordance  with  which 
everything  takes  place;  in  other  words,  the  power  of  nature  itself. 
And  so  the  natural  right  of  universal  nature,  and  consequently  of  every 
individual  thing,  extends  as  far  as  its  power :  and  accordingly,  what 
ever  any  man  does  after  the  laws  of  his  nature,  he  does  by  the  highest 
natural  right,  and  he  has  as  much  right  over  nature  as  he  has  power/'1 
On  this  ground  is  rested  man's  right  over  nature.  "  If  two  come 
together  and  unite  their  strength,  they  jointly  have  more  power,  and 
consequently  more  right  over  nature,  than  both  of  them  separately,  and 
the  more  there  are  that  have  so  joined  in  alliance,  the  more  right  they 
all  collectively  will  possess."2  And  on  no  different  ground  is  rested 
the  right  of  the  state  over  its  individual  members.  "...  As 
each  individual  in  the  state  of  nature,  so  the  body  and  mind  of  a 
dominion  have  as  much  right  as  they  have  power.  And  thus  each 
single  citizen  or  subject  has  the  less  right,  the  more  the  common 
wealth  exceeds  him  in  power,  and  each  citizen  consequently  does  and 
has  nothing  but  what  he  may  by  the  general  decree  of  the  common 
wealth  defend."3  "...  Whatever  he  [each  individual]  is 
ordered  by  the  general  consent,  he  is  bound  to  execute,  or  may  right 
fully  be  compelled  thereto."4  So  that  it  is  quite  inconceivable  that 
"  every  citizen  should  be  allowed  to  interpret  the  commonwealth's 
decrees  or  laws  "  and  thus  "  be  his  own  judge."5 — It  will  be  noted 

1  Tract.  Pol.  II.  §§  3  and  4.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  292. 

2  Ibid.  II.  §  13.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  296. 

3  Ibid.  III.  §  2.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  301. 

4  Ibid.  II.  §  16.    Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  297. 

5  Ibid.  III.  (esp.  §  4-Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  302). 

189 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

exactly  why  this  doctrine  is  referred  to  here.  It  is  not  for  the  purpose 
of  criticising  Spinoza's  strong  assertion  of  the  right  of  the  state  over 
the  individual.  A  sovereignty  of  the  state  over  the  individual  there 
must  be,  if  civil  society  is  to  exist  at  all.  But  what  we  have  to  mark 
is  that  the  particular  way  in  which  Spinoza  here  gains  a  theory  of 
sovereignty,  constitutes  not  an  advance  in  the  process  of  restoring  the 
cogito  to  its  rights,  but  rather  a  relapse  toward  the  point  of  view  of 
the  "  second  metaphysic." 

Let  us  pass,  then,  from  Spinoza's  political  views  to  the  last  of  the 
three  subjects  upon  which  we  have  here  to  touch — namely,  to  his 
conception  of  religion.1  If  it  was  true  that  in  the  state  we  find  the 
cogito  going  forth  from  itself  and  building  up  a  great  objective 
structure  in  whose  life  it  realises  its  own  being,  even  more  is  this  same 
thing  true  in  religion.  For  in  religion  the  rational  spirit  not  only 
builds  up  great  objective  structures.  It  not  only  organises  men,  and 
establishes  customs,  and  founds  institutions.  But  it  does  all  these 
things,  not  from  a  point  of  view  limited  to  this  present  life,  but  from  the 
point  of  view  of  that  total  or  eternal  life  which  is  the  real  life  of  man. 
That  is,  it  tries  to  take  the  highest  and  ultimate  point  of  view,  and 
from  that  point  of  view  to  organise  man's  life  and  to  fashion  man's 
society.  In  doing  this,  it  even  seeks  to  make  the  state  its  minister, 
and  to  make  man's  political  life  a  phase  or  aspect  of  his  total,  or 
religious,  life.  Nor,  ultimately,  can  this  be  avoided.  It  is  true,  com 
promises,  and  divisions  of  the  field  between  religion  and  politics,  may 
be  useful  or  even  necessary  in  this  present  life.  But  ultimately 
religion  cannot  leave  outside  of  itself  anything  whatsoever  which  is 
human.  It  must  either  seek  to  shape  the  whole  life  of  man;  or  else 
acknowledge  that  the  point  of  view  from  which  it  is  endeavouring  to 
organise  man's  life  is  not  the  highest  and  is  not  ultimate. 

But  it  follows  from  this  that  an  adequate  theory  of  religion  would 
complete  that  process  which  an  adequate  theory  of  the  state  would 
have  carried  part  way: — the  process  of  restoring  the  cogito  to  that 
supreme  place  in  philosophy,  from  which  Descartes,  with  the  best  of 
intentions  toward  it,  had  been  the  means  of  pulling  it  down.  But 

i  With  this  and  the  immediately  following  paragraphs,  compare  what  is  said  on  pp. 
195-198  infra,  concerning  a  contribution  ultimately  made  to  religion  by  the  "second 
metaphysic." 

190 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

what  we  have  already  seen  will  guard  us  from  expecting  any  such 
adequate  theory  from  Spinoza.  He  really  has  two  views  of  the  religious 
life,  as  Pfleiderer  points  out.1  And  these  both  lead  us  back  to  the 
discussions  just  examined,,  rather  than  forward  to  a  still  fuller 
possession  of  the  new  point  of  view.  The  one  refers  us  to  the  theory 
of  the  state.  The  other  takes  us  back  to  the  theory  of  the  individual's 
summum  bonum. 

In  the  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  Spinoza  views  religion  as 
obedience  to  the  divine  commands,,  as  a  life  of  practical  piety.  This 
life  of  piety  he  sunders  quite  sharply,  indeed  sunders  absolutely,  from 
philosophical  insight.  If  it  be  guided  by  revelation,  that  revelation 
itself  is  received  under  the  form  of  imagination,  not  under  that  of 
reason.  And,  as  we  have  already  seen,  its  rites  and  outward  observ 
ances,  are  to  be  in  accordance  with  the  public  peace  and  well-being, 
and  are  therefore  to  be  determined  by  the  sovereign  power  alone;  i.e., 
as  the  rational  organisation  of  man's  life  the  state  is  both  wider  and 
deeper  than  the  church  and  includes  the  church.  Indeed,  religion  in 
this  sense  is  doubly  sundered  from  reason.  Not  only  is  it  insisted 
that  philosophical  insight  is  not  its  basis  or  source  (so  that  Philosophy 
and  Theology  stand  altogether  apart).  But  the  separation  is  made  so 
absolute  that  reason  is  regarded  as  incapable  of  showing  us  this  way 
of  salvation  at  all.2  So  that,  in  what  is  the  especial  work  of  Spinoza's 
"  third  metaphysic  " — the  work,  namely,  of  putting  thought  in  its  true 
place  in  the  system  of  reality — this  part  of  his  theory  of  religion  can 
scarcely  be  said  to  take  us  any  farther  than  did  his  theory  of  the  state. 

But,  besides  this,  Spinoza  has  another  view  of  religion.  This  is 
brought  forward  in  those  closing  pages  of  the  Ethics  where  the  theory 
of  the  summum  bonum  receives  that  final  development  which  trans 
forms  it  into  a  theory  of  religion.  In  the  third  of  those  three  kinds  of 
knowledge  which  he  has  distinguished  in  the  De  Intellectus  Emenda- 
tione.,3  we  know  things  under  the  form  of  eternity ;  that  is  to  say,  we 

1  Philosophy  of  Religion  on  the  Basis  of  its  History,  (Eng.  tr.  from  2nd  German  ed., 
vol.  I.,  p.  62). 

2  Tract.  Theol.-Pol.  cap.  XV.  (see  especially  Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  194  and  p.  198,  along  with 
Spinoza's  annotation  in  loc.—  Elwes,  vol.  I.,  p.  276  [25],  Van    Vloten  et  Land,  vol.  I.,  p. 
625  [xxxi]). 

3  See  Elwes,  vol.  IT.,  p.  8  seq.     Four  kinds  of  "perception  or  knowledge  "  are  men 
tioned  in  this  passage  ;  but  Spinoza  usually  groups  these  as  three  (see  Eth.  II.  40,  schol.  2  ; 
V.  25-28,  31-33). 

191 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

know  them  in  God.  But  thus  to  know  things  is  truly  to  know  God. 
This,  furthermore,  is  our  perfection,  and  we  joy  in  it.  This  joy  is 
attended  by  the  idea  of  God  as  its  cause.  And  this,  according  to 
Spinoza's  definition,1  is  love.  Thus  arises  that  unselfish  and  disinter 
ested  intellectual  love  of  God2  which  does  not  expect  or  endeavour  to 
be  loved  by  God  in  return.3 

In  this  intellectual  love  of  God  consists  the  essence  of  religion 
according  to  Spinoza's  second  conception  of  it.  How  high  and  pure 
and  disinterested  this  conception  is;  how  this  lofty  disinterestedness 
is  seen  also  in  his  theory  of  immortality  ;4  how  in  later  days  great  poets 
and  teachers  were  touched  by  it : — these  are  topics  upon  which  any  lover 
of  Spinoza  would  gladly  linger.  To  turn  away  from  them  to  the  work 
of  criticism  seems  almost  like  ingratitude.  Yet  if  we  are  to  learn 
from  Spinoza  that  which  Spinoza  has  to  teach,  we  must  repeat 
even  here  the  question  which  especially  concerns  us  as  we  discuss  his 
"  third  metaphysic."  How  far,  then,  does  this  conception  take  us  in 
restoring  the  cogito  to  its  place  as  a  principle  of  philosophical  explana 
tion,  and  thus  in  giving  to  reason  its  due  place  in  the  system  of 
reality  ? 

The  answer  is,  that  it  really  takes  us  no  farther  in  this  direction 
than  did  the  theory  of  individual  morality.  This  intellectualistic 
religion  is  the  bloom  upon  that  intellectualistic  summum  ~bonum.  No 
more  here  than  there  can  reason  be  pourtrayed  going  forth  from  itself 
and  building  those  great  structures  of  church  and  state  in  which  it 
realises  its  nature  and  fulfils  the  law  of  its  being.  This,  as  Pfleiderer 
points  out,5  is  the  reason  why  Spinoza  is  never  able  to  bring  into 
organic  relation  the  two  kinds  of  religion  which  he  has  described :  this 
intellectualistic  religion  to  which  men  of  disciplined  mind  may  attain, 
and  which  requires  no  institutions;  and  that  religion  of  the  many, 
described  in  the  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,  which  has  a  revela 
tion,  and  institutions,  and  a  social  organisation.6 

1  The  sixth  of  the  definitions  of  the  emotions  appended  to  Eth.  III.     Cf.  III.  13.  schol. 

2  Eth.  V.  15. 

3  Eth.  V.  19. 

4  Eth.  V.  21-23,  29-31,  3840,  and  specially  41. 

5  Op.  cit.,  (Eng.  tr.,  vol.  I.,  pp.  65,  66). 

6  Now  that  the  three  tendencies  in  Spinoza's  thinking  are  before  us,  the  position  of  the 
second  relatively  to  the  other  two  may  be  indicated  in  this  way :— It  stands  midway 

192 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

VIII. 

Such,  then,  was  the  place  occupied  by  Spinoza  in  that  process  of 
development  which  is  the  history  of  philosophy.  Descartes,  standing 
in  the  forefront  of  a  new  age  and  seized  to  his  heart's  core  by  its  spirit, 
had  attempted  to  take  his  stand  as  if  at  the  very  beginnings  of 
science;  had  attempted  to  free  himself  from  all  assumptions,  and  to 
show  forth  the  bare  fact  as  he  found  it.  He  could  not,  it  is  true, 
annihilate  the  past.  He  could  not  put  himself  back  where  Vedic  poet 
or  Ionic  cpvffioXoyos  had  stood.  The  cogito  became  self-conscious  in 
him  as  it  could  not  in  them.  But  though  his  material  was  so  different 
from  theirs,  yet  in  dealing  with  it  he  put  himself  nearly  upon  the  same 
logical  level  as  they;  he  used  the  same  order  of  categories,  and  so 
followed  essentially  the  same  method  of  conceiving  reality.  But  while 
it  was  thus  given  to  him  to  initiate  the  first  stage  of  modern  philosophy, 
it  was  not  given  to  him  to  carry  it  through  to  its  conclusion.  To 
develop  the  full  significance  of  the  categories  which  dominated  it;  to 
carry  its  method  through  to  a  final  result;  to  formulate  this  result 
fearlessly  and  uncompromisingly,  turning  aside  for  no  influence  either 
of  church  or  of  state;  and  thus,  with  the  emphasis  of  a  final  word,  to 
make  clear  what  the  ultimate  outcome  is  of  this  way  of  attempting  to 
get  at  the  truth  of  our  experience : — this  was  reserved  for  Spinoza. 

between  the  first  and  the  third  in  the  sense  that,  in  working  out  its  view  of  the  world  as 
one,  it  keeps  its  hold  upon  certain  parts  and  aspects  of  the  manifold,  but  makes  abstraction 
of  other  parts  and  aspects.  And  those  of  which  it  makes  abstraction  are  precisely  those 
which,  as  human  development  goes  on,  come  more  and  more  to  be  the  supreme  interests 
of  men.  Yet  even  in  this  (so  long  as  the  scientific  interest  in  the  details  of  the  world 
remains  dominant)  its  face  must  be  regarded  as  turned  toward  the  third  rather  than 
toward  the  first.  For  though  it  abstracts  from  the  aspects  of  reality  just  referred  to,  and 
leaves  no  home  for  them  in  the  One  (and  therefore  cannot  in  their  nature  find  a  key 
to  the  nature  of  the  One),  yet  it  does  this,  not  in  the  sense  of  making  a  conscious 
and  intentional  abstraction,  such  as  he  makes  who  believes  abstraction  to  be 
the  sole  way  to  truth ;  but  only  in  the  sense  that  it  has  never  seen  them,  has  never 
felt  the  pressure  of  the  problem  which  they  raise.  And  such  abstraction  is  likely  to  be 
overcome  in  the  end.  For  if  any  aspect  at  all  of  the  manifold  be  admitted  into  the 
One,  the  other  aspects,  coming  forward  each  in  its  own  time,  may  be  depended  upon  to 
enforce  their  claims  with  an  emphasis  that  increases  with  the  deepening  of  human 
experience,  and  at  last  becomes  irresistible.  But  the  conscious  and  thoroughgoing 
abstraction  which  the  first  tendency  makes  is  a  different  matter.  By  its  very  nature  it 
lies  almost  beyond  correction  through  any  art  of  persuasion.  For  of  what  avail  is  logical 
refutation  against  a  man  who  has  found  that  human  thought  and  speech  cannot  express 
that  which  alone  is  real,  and  in  union  with  which  is  the  only  true  life  of  the  soul  ? 

14  193 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

And  this  alone  would  make  him,  in  the  history  of  thought,  one  of 
that  small  number  of  abiding  figures  with  which  it  is  the  primary 
task  of  the  student  of  the  history  of  philosophy  to  deal.  But  there  is 
more  than  that.  In  carrying  the  logic  of  Cartesianism  forward  to  its 
conclusion,  he  was  no  Wolff  rounding  out  the  teaching  of  a  great 
master  and  destroying  its  vitality  in  the  process.  On  the  contrary,  his 
was  an  original  and  searching  intellect,  having  life  in  itself,  and  driven 
by  its  own  inner  forces  to  penetrate  to  the  elements  of  things.  Hence 
it  was  impossible  for  him  to  stop  short  with  that  acosmic  or  mystic 
view  which  is  the  ultimate  outcome  of  the  Cartesian  way  of  dealing 
with  experience  and  the  experienced  world.  Other  types  of  thought 
found  a  place  in  his  mind  and  won  from  him  an  adherence  which  was 
perfectly  sincere:  the  naturalistic  spirit  of  modern  science  made  its 
appeal  to  him,  and,  in  defiance  of  the  logic  which  required  an  abstract 
Absolute,  he  made  the  One  Substance  the  home  of  innumerable  modes, 
and  gave  to  each  mode  its  conatus  in  suo  esse  perseverandi;  and  he 
even  has  glimpses  of  the  Idealistic  insight  that  spirit  or  reason  is  the 
reality  of  all  things,  and  the  active  agent  in  all  cosmic  processes. 

Of  such  an  historical  position  the  result  is  that  he  who  makes 
Spinoza  his  companion  makes  the  greatest  things  in  philosophy  his 
companions.  On  one  side,  he  finds  himself  brought  into  touch  with 
the  austere  and  immemorial  thought  of  Vedantist  and  Eleatic  and 
Mystic.  On  another,  he  is  linked,  by  affinity  rather  than  by  similarity, 
with  that  long  succession  of  men  of  thought  whose  greatest  name  is 
still  that  of  Democritus — the  men  who  seek  to  interpret  the  world,  or 
various  aspects  of  it,  by  the  conception-  of  a  natural  necessity  acting 
a  tergo.1  And  on  still  another  side — or  rather  in  his  final  attitude 
when  he  seeks  to  take  into  himself  Spinoza's  thought  as  a  whole — he 
finds  himself  with  his  face  set  toward  Kant,  and  toward  that  still 
greater  man  of  thought  who  articulated  Kant's  deepest  insight  into  a 
systematic  view  of  the  world  and  of  the  world's  history. 

And  the  way  in  which  Spinoza's  system — indeed,  the  way  in  which 

i  Affinity  but  not  similarity.— The  Spinoza  of  the  "second  metaphysic  "  agrees  with 
these  men  of  science  in  attempting  to  explain  the  actual  system  of  things  by  a  necessity 
which  (1)  is  immanent,  (2)  acts  a  tergo.  But  he  differs  from  them  in  that  he  takes  the 
divine  nature  itself  as  the  home  and  seat  of  this  necessity.  He,  if  one  may  so  speak,  lifts 
his  Democriteanism  into  the  very  nature  of  God,  and  values  it  as  the  true  interpretation 
of  that  nature. 

194 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OP    SPINOZA 

the  whole  movement  from  Descartes  to  Spinoza — thus  cries  out  for 
Kant,  is  in  one  sense  the  most  important  point  of  all  for  the  student 
of  Spinoza.  For  if  we  would  understand  a  system  in  which  diverse 
aspects  stand  unreconciled  side  by  side,  we  must  gain  a  point  of  view 
above  the  diversities.  We  must  gain  a  point  of  view  from  which  we 
can  see  how  they  came  to  be  what  they  are ;  and  what  the  failure  and 
yet  the  relative  justification  of  each  is;  and  how  they  may  all  be 
taken  up  into  a  greater  and  more  comprehensive  system  which  will 
give  to  each  its  due  without  sanctioning  the  error  which  each  has 
when  it  attempts  to  stand  alone  and  to  make  itself  a  finality.  And 
precisely  the  way  to  gain  such  a  point  of  view  for  the  study  of  Spinoza 
is,  first  to  make  one's  journey  from  him  to  Kant  and  Hegel ;  and  then 
from  these  back  again  to  Spinoza,  in  order  to  interpret  him  in  the  light 
gained"  from  those  who  finally  satisfied  the  need  which  he  intensified. 

But  that  brings  us  to  our  last  question.  Let  us  suppose  that  the 
journey  just  mentioned  has  been  made.  Let  us  suppose  that  Kant 
and  the  Kantians  have  done  their  work,  and  that  we  are  viewing  things 
from  the  new  point  of  view  thus  made  possible  to  us.  Is  there  not 
still — so  our  question  would  run — a  great  lesson  for  us  to  learn  from 
Spinoza;  a  lesson  which  we  can  learn  all  the  better  now;  which, 
indeed,  we  could  not  have  learned  properly  at  all  had  not  Kant  come 
to  teach  us  ?  Leaving  the  purely  historical  interest  aside,  and  thinking 
only  of  our  own  outlook  upon  our  world,  is  there  not  still  a  great 
reason  why  we  should  continue  our  pilgrimages  to  Spinoza?  A  brief 
consideration  of  certain  facts  will  show  us  that  to  this  question  we 
must  give  an  affirmative  answer. 

First,  since  Kant  and  Hegel,  we  can  no  longer  separate  God  and 
the  world  in  the  way  which  was  once  thought  agreeable  to  truth  and 
necessary  to  religion.  We  may  say  that  God  is  the  subject  of  the 
world ;  or  that  the  world  is  God's  thought,  or  God's  activity,  or  God's 
objective  consciousness.  Or  we  may  prefer  to  retain  a  theological  term 
and  say  that  the  world  is  a  continuous  creation.  But  however  "we 
phrase  it,  we  cannot  escape  from  the  position  that  God  and  the  world 
stand  in  organic  relation. 

But,  secondly,  it  follows  from  this  that   we  can  no    longer  think 
highly  of  God  by  thinking  meanly  of  the  world.     On  the  contrary,  to 

195 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

think  meanly  of  the  world  is  to  think  meanly  of  God.  If,  then,  we 
would  retain  those  high  thoughts  concerning  God  which  the  men  of 
the  heroic  ages  of  religion  had,  we  must  gain  high  thoughts  of  the 
world  such  as  those  men  had  not.  And  there  is  one  aspect  of 
Spinoza's  thought  which  helps  us  to  gain  just  such  thoughts1 — the 
aspect  which  comes  especially  forward  in  what  we  have  been  calling 
his  "  second  metaphysic."  The  way  upward  from  the  medieval  view  of 
this  present  world  and  of  nature,  to  juster  views  of  these,  was  a  long 
and  arduous  way.  It  called  for  brave  soldiers  in  the  "  war  of  the  liber 
ation  of  humanity."  Of  these  Spinoza  was  one ;  and  this  seemingly  so 
anti-religious  "  second  metaphysic  "  was  precisely  one  of  his  instru 
ments  in  that  war.  The  peculiar  form  of  the  category  of  cause 
employed  in  this  metaphysic  is  indeed  inadequate  to  the  matter  to  be 
comprehended.  But  even  with  this  inadequate  category  Spinoza  makes 
plain  the  greatness  of  the  world,  and  the  majesty  of  those  laws  which 
are  changeless  and  inviolable  just  because  they  are  expressions  of  the 
necessity  of  the  Divine  nature. 

"  But,"  it  may  be  urged,  "  the  metaphysic  in  question  has  been  the 
choice  weapon,  not  of  the  merely  irreligious,  but  of  the  positively  and 
avowedly  anti-religious,  in  all  the  great  ages  of  human  culture.  Is 
there  not  something  paradoxical  in  the  statement  that  precisely  by  this 
metaphysic  Spinoza  made  a  great  and  lasting  contribution  to  the 
deepest  spiritual  needs  of  man  ?  You  say  that  in  Spinoza  we  have,  on 
the  one  side,  a  man  of  religion — a  man  who  expresses  religion  '  in  its 
most  concentrated  and  exclusive  form  .  .  .  that  attitude  of  the 
mind  in  which  all  other  relations  are  swallowed  up  in  the  relation  of 
the  soul  to  God '  ;2  while,  on  the  other  side,  we  have  a  man  of  natural 
istic  temper  whose  business  it  was  to  explain  nature  as  a  system  of 
necessitated  modes.  And  then  you  say  that  it  is  the  latter,  rather  than 
the  former,  who  has  contributed  to  modern  religion.  Surely  this  is 
paradox.  Or  is  your  meaning  simply  this :  that  modern  man  can  gain 
from  a  naturalistic  metaphysic  what  Spinoza  himself  frequently  seems 

1  Cf.  p.   vii.   of  the  Preface  to  the  second  edition  (1894)  of  Mr.  Hale  White's  transla 
tion  of  the  Ethics. 

2  From  the  Master  of  Balliol's  apt  definition  of  Mysticism  (Evolution  of  Theology  in 
the  Greek  Philosophers,  vol.  II.,  p.  210).    Cf.  the  following  reference  to  Spinoza's  "Athe 
ism  "— "  In  him  the  tendency  to  unity,  to  the  infinite,  to  religion,  overbalanced  itself,  till, 
by  mere  excess  it  seemed  to  be  changed  into  its  own  opposite."     (Philosophy  of  Kant, 

"    -sgow,  1877,  p.  43. ) 

196 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

to  gain  from  it — the  Stoic  peace  which,  arises  from  the  very  thought  of 
the  necessity  that  is  in  the  world,  and  from  the  insight  that  no  freedom 
is  desirable  except  the  freedom  obtained  by  adopting  this  necessity  as 
one's  own  law  ?" 

No,  the  answer  must  run,  that  is  not  what  is  meant.  The  Stoic  faith 
that  the  necessity  of  nature  is  the  wisest  and  kindliest  and  most  reason 
able  of  all  things ;  and  the  resolute  peace  which  such  faith  brings : — 
these,  it  is  true,  one  can  learn  from  Spinoza.  But  what  is  here  in  view  is 
something  different:  this,  namely, — present-day  religion  and  theology 
can  learn,  and  have  learned,  a  lesson  from  Spinoza,  but  the  lesson  itself 
has  been  determined  not  so  much  by  what  Spinoza  has  to  give  as  by 
what  the  modern  world  is  able  to  receive.  For  the  characteristic 
devotion  of  modern  men  is  to  their  intellectual  and  practical  citizen 
ship  in  this  present  world.  They  cannot  neglect  the  creature  in  order 
to  find  the  Creator.  They  cannot  turn  away  from  the  world;  what 
they  seek,  alike  in  thought,  in  labour,  in  religion,  is  the  mastery  of  it. 
It  is  true,  indeed,  as  already  we  have'  had  occasion  to  notice,1  that 
Mysticism  is  not  without  its  place  among  modern  men.  That  ancient 
spirit  still  passes  to  and  fro,  finding  in  solitary  hearts  and  in  quiet 
societies  its  chosen,  and  bidding  them,  if  they  would  truly  live,  to  lose 
themselves,  not  in  the  great  energies  of  the  world,  but  in  God.  And 
if  we  had  among  us  Mystics  in  the  greatness  of  the  ancient  pattern — a 
Bernard  or  an  Eckhart — they  might  be  powerful  by  the  mere  weight 
of  their  practical  example.  Their  devotion  to  ends  intangible  to  us, 
their  absolute  rejection  of  goods  that  we  take  for  granted  as  the  true 
goods  of  life,  might  shock  and  surprise  us  into  a  re-examination  of 
our  lives  and  into  a  questioning  of  our  habitual  "  scale  of  values." 
But  the  fact  remains,  that  from  Mysticism,  in  the  full  and  historical 
sense  of  the  name,  the  modern  world  is  virtually  incapable  of  learn 
ing.  And  from  this  it  follows  at  once  that  when  modern  men  make  a 
pilgrimage  to  Spinoza,  it  is  not  to  the  Spinoza  of  the  "  first  meta- 
physic." 

But  the  need  of  which  the  modern  world  is  conscious,  in  the  realm 
where  thought  and  religion  meet,  is  this. — What  is  wrought  into  the1 
very  texture  of  the  modern  mind  is  the  idea  of  natural  law.  Hence,, 

l  Supra,  pp.  151, 152. 
197 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

if  religion  is  to  be,  not  a  mere  partisan  fighting  for  its  existence,  but 
the  rightful  and  undoubted  master  of  life,  we  must  be  enabled  to  see 
natural  law  as  a  way  of  God,  and  the  uniformity  of  natural  law  as  an 
appropriate  expression  of  the  rationality  of  God — an  appropriate 
expression  of  a  divine  reason  which,  being  absolutely  perfect,  cannot 
be  capricious  or  arbitrary,  and  which  is  immanent  in  the  whole  of 
nature.  I  do  not  mean  to  say  that  this  is  the  precise  point  of  view 
taken  by  Spinoza  in  his  "  second  metaphysic  " ;  at  any  rate,  it  is  not 
the  form  of  expression  there  used.  But  it  is  the  lesson  which  the 
wisest  and  most  sensitive  of  modern  leaders  of  religious  thought  have 
been  able  to  learn  from  this  aspect  of  Spinoza's  teaching — leaders  of 
whom  Herder,  who  was  half  theologian  and  half  poet,  and,  therefore, 
eminently  fitted  to  learn  valuable  lessons  in  Spinoza's  school,  is  a 
representative.1 

Such,  on  this  side  of  its  history,  has  been  the  strange  outcome  of 
the  thought  of  Spinoza.  It  had  in  it  a  metaphysic  which,  to  use 
words  already  quoted,  is  the  theoretical  expression  of  religion  "  in  its 
most  concentrated  and  exclusive  form  " ;  and  it  had  in  it  a  metaphysic 
which  for  centuries  has  been  denounced  as  atheistic  and  anti-religious. 
And  of  these  two  it  was  the  latter,  and  not  the  former,  which  (through 
men  such  as  those  just  referred  to — men  of  Herder's  type)  entered 
beneficently  into  modern  religious  thinking,  and  helped  in  making 
possible  that  insight  which  the  world  needed  for  composing  the  strife 
between  science  and  religion.  For  men  who  are  in  earnest  about 
religion — specially  for  men  who  are  concerned  with  its  intellectual 
defense,  or  with  interpreting  it  to  new  generations  and  changed  minds 
—few  facts  are  more  full  of  instruction  and  of  warning  than  this.  It 
shows,  for  one  thing,  what  mere  sincerity  in  thinking  can  do.  From 

i  It  is  a  lesson  which  can  be  learned  also  from  Wordsworth  ;  in  fact,  in  Wordsworth  it 
has  its  highest  and  soundest  form.  And  it  can  be  learned  from  Goethe ;  but  those  whose 
good  opinion  is  most  worth  having  will  not  censure  me  if  I  prefer— though  it  would  be  a 
happiness  to  be  able  to  use  gentler  words  in  speaking  of  the  great  German  to  whom  all 
thoughtful  modern  men,  whether  they  like  it  or  no,  are  profoundly  indebted— a  single 
touch  of  the  pure  heart  and  upright  spirit  of  Wordsworth,  to  all  that  vast  intelligence, 
all  that  comprehension  of  the  world  from  the  point  of  view  of  art,  for  which  the  name 
of  Goethe  stands.  Wordsworth's  spirit  not  only  is  morally  higher,  but  it  also  brings  a 
.sounder  and  truer  understanding  of  the  real  nature  of  the  world.  For  the  real  nature 
of  the  world  is,  if  I  may  be  allowed  such  an  expression,  passionately  moral.  And  this 
Wordsworth  knew ;  and  so  did  Plato ;  but  Goethe  did  not. 

198 


THE    METAPHYSIC    OF    SPINOZA 

anything  that  seemed  to  be  truth,  or  to  be  an  aspect  of  truth,  Spinoza 
would  not  turn  away.  No  matter  how  austere  its  countenance,  he  not 
merely  received  it,  but  made  it  a  welcome  guest.  And  the  result  was 
that,  from  a  seemingly  "  anti-religious "  view,  later  generations 
learned  a  lesson  which  was  in  the  most  fundamental  way  serviceable 
to  religion.  And  it  shows  another  thing:  apologists  who  imagine 
that  religion  can  go  forward  only  over  the  dead  body  of  some  scientific 
truth  have  comprehended  neither  the  depth  nor  the  breadth  of  that 
which  they  have  taken  it  as  their  life-work  to  defend.  Eeligion  has 
few  more  injurious  friends  than  those  who  are  strong  in  attacking 
opponents,  but  weak  in  comprehending  and  interpreting  their  own 
position. 


199 


PLATO  AND   THE   FOUNDING  OF   IDEALISM 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM.1 

IN  the  pathetic  and  winning  history  of  Mysticism  one  of  the  most 
marked  features  is  a  certain  impersonality.  Not  that  Mysticism  has 
been  without  its  special  champions ;  in  its  history  there  are  outstand 
ing  figures — the  great  and  daring  men  of  thought  who  clung  to  the 
hope  of  union  with  reality,,  even  while  they  were  formulating  the  world- 
shattering  logic  which  puts  reality  beyond  the  reach  of  all  the  normal 
forms  and  energies  of  our  experience.  But  these  are  not  so  much 
individual  men  of  thought  who  by  their  own  labour  make  their  way 
to  a  new  insight,  and  win  a  generation  to  it,  and  so  become  the  founders 
of  a  school  and  a  tradition.  Eather  they  are  voices  for  some 
thing  wider  than  themselves ;  something  that  works  dimly  in  the  mind 
of  an  age,  like  a  hidden  ferment,  and  slowly  gathers  shape,  and  comes 
at  last  to  the  spoken  word.  When  some  great  race  finds  life  an  unsat 
isfied  hunger  or  a  burden  of  pain;  when  some  great  civilisation,  with 
all  its  skill  and  wealth  and  luxury,  weighs  itself  in  the  balances  and 
finds  itself  wanting;  when  some  generation,  possessed  by  the  vision 
and  the  passion  of  religion,  finds  its  established  religion  a  thing 
external,  ceremonial,  priestly: — then,  as  by  an  original  tendency  of 
human  nature,  and  with  no  need  of  historical  support  or  derivation,  the 
temper  of  Mysticism  arises  like  a  spirit  moving  upon  the  face  of  the 
deep ;  and,  having  arisen,  finds  its  prophets.  It  is  the  business  of  the 
Idealist  to  persuade  and  convince  men,  as  best  he  can,  under  all  cir 
cumstances  and  in  every  spiritual  climate;  but  the  Mystic  speaks 
usually  to  hearts  made  ready  for  his  word ;  and,  to  them,  speaks  with 
overwhelming  power.  Indeed,  the  passage  of  mystic  doctrine  from 
land  to  land  and  age  to  age  has  seldom  been  more  aptly  described 

1 1  am  indebted  to  the  Delegates  of  the  Clarendon  Press  for  the  generous  permission 
which  has  enabled  me  to  quote  from  Jowett's  translation, 

203 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

than  by  Professor  Royce,1  when  he  calls  to  our  minds  the  words  of 
Coleridge's  Ancient  Mariner: 

I  pass,  like  night,  from  land  to  land  ; 
I  have  strange  power  of  speech  ; 
That  moment  that  his  face  I  see, 
I  know  the  man  that  must  hear  me  : 
To  him  my  tale  I  teach. 

The  history  of  Idealism  has  been  very  different.  He  who  first 
formulated  it,  formulated  it  by  the  energies  of  the  constructive 
reason  in  him ;  and  formulated  it  well-nigh  for  ever.  To  its  funda 
mental  positions  he  worked  his  way  slowly,  sounding  onward  as 
through  an  unknown  sea ;  availing  himself  of  the  diverse  results  of  the 
earlier  science  of  his  race,  but  going  far  beyond  anything  of  which  it 
even  had  dreamed;  and  showing  himself  so  pre-eminent  in  the  power 
and  insight  of  the  labouring  reason  that  since  his  day  Idealism  has 
never  departed  without  profound  loss  from  what  is  essential  in  his 
method  and  teaching,  nor  returned  without  receiving  the  touch  and 
the  inspiration  of  a  new  life. 

In  the  first  place,  he  fixed  for  ever  the  scientific  point  of  departure 
of  Idealism — the  question  how  our  knowledge  is  possible.  Then,  pro 
ceeding  from  that  point  of  departure,  he  not  only  moved  in  the  true 
direction  in  his  attempt  to  comprehend  the  nature  of  reality  and  the 
meaning  of  our  life,  but  moved  so  far  in  that  true  direction  that  the 
way  was  made  easy  to  all  who  in  later  days  could  enter  into  his  teach 
ing  as  it  really  was.  And  another  thing  he  did,  in  which  his  greatness 
as  the  founder  of  Idealism  culminates.  He  stated  his  view  of  the 
world  with  a  grace  of  temper,  an  elevation  of  soul,  a  prophetic  and 
compelling  passion,  such  as  gave  to  his  truth  a  double  power  and  made 
it  to  the  men  of  later  ages  an  illumination  and  an  austere  allurement, 
a  persuasion  and  a  rebuke. 

This  Plato  did;  being  one  of  those  rare  and  most  mighty  spirits 
in  whom  the  gifts  and  the  insights  that  are  given  singly  to  other  men, 
appear  in  combination,  and  in  that  combination  take  on  a  new  and 
greater  power,  each  contributing  to  the  other,  each  enlightening  the 

i  The  World  and  the  Individual,  First  Series,  p.  85. 
204 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

other,  each  deepening  the  other.  First,  there  came  to  union  in  him 
the  two  great  scientific  currents  in  which  the  constructive  thinking  of 
the  Greeks  had  hitherto  run :  the  older  metaphysic,  Ionian  or  Italian, 
which  sought  to  comprehend  the  universe  as  a  universe ;  and  the  newer 
Socratic  "  way  of  ideas."  In  this  combination  each  side  found  its  true 
fulfilment  in  the  other,  so  that,  in  the  place  of  two  brilliant  but  limited 
endeavours,  there  arose  a  single  complete  and  solidly  based  and 
thoroughly  luminous  view  of  the  world.  Then,  secondly,  this  synthesis 
itself  was  part  of  a  still  wider  synthesis.  On  the  one  side,  as  the 
achievement  just  referred  to  indicates,  he  had  in  him  the  scientific 
mind.  He  had  its  intellectual  disinterestedness,  its  passion  after 
knowledge  for  its  own  sake,  its  instinct  for  looking  straight  upon  facts 
and  seeing  them  with  clear  eyes  just  as  they  are;  he  inherited,  in  a 
word,  not  simply  the  results  of  the  previous  scientific  history  of  the 
Greeks,  but  also  their  scientific  temper  in  the  very  perfection  of  those 
qualities  which  have  made  the  Hellenic  mind  to  all  ages  the  pattern 
of  the  scientific  mind.  But  he  was  possessed  also,  and  to  the  very 
centre  of  his  being,  by  the  great  practical  passions:  by  the  passion, 
moral  and  political,  which  seeks  to  shape  life  and  the  social  organisa 
tion  of  life  according  to  the  good ;  and  by  the  religious  passion  which 
apprehends,  as  the  good,  the  ultimate  principle  of  the  universe,  and 
thus  sets  the  whole  of  man's  life  in  the  light  of  a  heavenly  vision,  and 
directs  all  his  energies  to  the  works  whose  significance  is  eternal.  And 
in  him  those  things— that  disinterested  scientific  temper,  that  passion 
ate  devotion  to  the  realisation  of  the  good,  and  that  profound  religious 
ness — were  not  warring  tendencies;  they  were  co-operating  powers, 
each  widening  the  scope  and  deepening  the  character  of  the  others. 
And  even  this  is  not  the  limit  of  the  union  and  co-operation  in  him  of 
characters  that  ordinarily  stand  apart.  Along  with  that  scientific 
intellect,  that  moral  and  political  and  religious  temper,  there  went 
the  mind  of  the  poet,  and  the  capacities,  both  receptive  and  active,  of 
the  artist.  And  this  side  of  his  nature,  once  more, — in  spite  of  the 
hostility  that  necessarily  existed  between  him  and  those  artists  of  his 
race  who  either  were  artists  and  nothing  more,  or  else  represented  a 
reason  earlier  and  unpurified  by  criticism — really  worked  together  with 
the  others.  He  was  half  poet ;  but  in  him  poetic  intuition  was  a  form 

205 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

of  intelligence,  rather  than  a  rival  of  intelligence;  and  so  the  poet 
in  him  made  him  a  greater,  not  a  less,  philosopher.  He  had  the  Ionian 
delight  in  beauty,  and  the  Ionian  command  over  the  powers  by  which 
beauty  is  expressed ;  but  he  had  also  the  earnestness  of  Lacedaemon — 
no  Dorian  saw  more  clearly  than  he  the  need  in  human  life  of  sim 
plicity,  of  austere  discipline,  of  that  gravity  of  mind  which  lifts  a  man 
above  luxury,  above  levity,  above  the  habit  of  imitation.  He  had  the 
unashamed  Greek  joy  in  the  whole  of  existence ;  yet  he  was  haunted  by 
a  vision  of  eternity  which  condemned  alike  the  world  that  now  is,  and 
the  mythology  of  his  race,  and  the  political  order  of  his  state.  He  had 
the  Greek  delight  in  life,  the  Greek  instinct  for  the  exercise  and 
development  of  all  the  faculties  of  the  soul,  the  catholic  Greek  sense 
for  completeness  and  integrity  of  life;  yet  he  knew  that  life  can 
reach  its  true  wholeness  and  integrity,  not  by  leaving  all  its  elements 
and  interests  upon  a  level,  but  only  by  recognising  the  good,  and 
putting  it  in  its  place  of  supremacy,  and  arranging  the  whole  of  life 
as  the  manifold  system  of  its  realisation. 

Such  was  the  many-sided  reason  that  dwelt  in  Plato  and  helped  to 
make  him  the  greatest  figure  in  the  long  history  of  philosophy.  But 
there  is  still  something  else.  A  metaphysician  is  a  man  who  seeks  to 
ascertain  the  true  meaning  of  our  experience.  And  the  man  who 
would  do  that,  must  have  more  than  scientific  temper  and  scientific 
ability,  more  than  a  wide  mind  and  large  capacities  of  reason;  per 
sonally  and  vitally  he  must  himself  possess,  on  all  its  greater  and 
constitutive  sides,  the  experience  into  whose  meaning  he  would  inquire. 
For  himself,  and  with  directness  and  integrity  of  devotion,  he  must 
have  walked  in  the  ways  of  life  and  have  taken  his  part  in  the  world's 
work.  And  this  requisite,  too,  was  fulfilled  in  Plato.  It  was  not  only 
that  he  was  man  of  science,  artist,  poet;  not  only  that  he  sustained 
the  part  of  friend  and  of  teacher;  but  his  heart  was  linked  to  the 
greater  causes  in  the  life  of  his  people ;  he  was  a  citizen  drawn  to  the 
welfare  of  the  Greek  states  with  an  intensity  of  earnestness  that  had 
in  it  the  possibility,  and  at  last  the  actuality,  of  tragic  pain.  He  not 
only  had  a  vision  of  perfection,  but  felt  the  call  to  realise  it ;  to  realise 
it  not  abstractly  nor  in  dream,  but  concretely  in  the  life  of  his  day — - 
in  the  education  which  lasts  from  birth  till  death,  and  in  the  order  of 

206 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

the  state.  He  did  not  rest,  as  Windelband  so  finely  points  out,1  in  his 
gaze  upon  the  supersensuous  world;  he  was  not  one  of  those  saints 
of  contemplation  who  "  receive  into  themselves  the  great  picture  of 
existence  and  contemplate  it  in  desireless  peace."  On  the  contrary, 
having  brought  from  the  eternal  realm  ideals  for  this,  he  took  up  "  with 
passionate  courage  the  struggle  against  the  powers  of  the  earth,"  and 
strove  "  with  all  the  energies  of  his  soul '  to  improve  and  to  convert '  the 
world  " ;  he  was — and  is — "  the  chief  of  all  the  spirits  who  exercise 
the  energies  of  will."  Such  he  was;  and  being  such,  there  was  no 
escape  for  him  from  the  wrestle  with  the  world,  no  standing  apart  from 
life,  no  remaining  untouched  by  the  storm  of  the  times. 

Thus,  then,  it  was,  that,  while  Spartan  armies  were  going  to  and 
fro  upon  the  soil  of  Attica,  there  was  given  to  the  world  in  Plato  its 
most  perfect  example,  not  of  philosophy  only,  but  of  the  philosophic 
mind.  He  was  a  great  man  of  science;  but  he  was  more;  he  was  a 
mighty  spirit,  taking  part  in  the  struggle  of  man  upon  the  earth,  and 
bringing  to  that  struggle  its  illumination  with  eternal  light.  And  so, 
too,  it  was  with  his  view  of  the  world  and  of  life ;  it  shows  the  intellect 
working  at  its  very  highest  power ;  but  it  is  more  than  a  work  of  the 
intellect.  It  is  the  passionate  vision  and  creation  of  the  entire  human 
soul ;  a  vision  and  creation  in  which  the  working  of  the  greater 
passions — the  passion  for  the  state,  the  passion  for  righteousness,  the 
passion  for  eternity — goes  hand  in  hand  with  the  highest  energy  of 
the  disinterested  intellect. 

In  attempting  to  understand  this  philosophy  of  Plato's  as  a  body 
of  doctrine — which  involves  not  merely  apprehending  Plato's  conclu 
sions,  but  apprehending  also  the  forces  and  tendencies  that  operated 
in  him  to  shape  them — we  have  three  things  to  remember  at  the  outset. 
First,  Plato  was  an  Idealist  from  the  beginning;  from  the  beginning 
the  root  of  the  matter  was  in  him — there  were  no  Kantian  wanderings. 
But  secondly,  his  Idealism  was  not  complete  from  the  beginning. 
The  Idealism  of  his  early  and  middle  years  had  in  it  an  incomplete 
ness  which  it  was  one  of  the  great  labours  of  his  later  years  to  remedy ; 

1  At  the  close  of  his  monograph  on  Plato  (Frommanns  Klassiker  der  Philosophic)— a. 
brief  but  most  admirable  account,  which  ought  to  be  translated  into  English. 

207 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

and  this  later  work  gave  to  the  whole  structure  of  his  philosophy  at 
once  greater  depth,  greater  concreteness,  and  greater  power.  While 
thirdly,  throughout  Plato's  whole  life  the  forces  that  make,  not  for 
Idealism  at  all,  but  for  Mysticism,  acted  upon  him  and  found  in  his 
soul  a  great  response. 

These  facts  give  us  our  plan  of  treatment.  We  are  to  consider  an 
Idealist;  but  one  whose  Idealism  (1)  stands  face  to  face  with  the 
great  opponent  of  Idealism,  (2)  undergoes  development  from  within. 
It  will  be  wise  to  take  the  discussion  in  three  steps :  (1)  To  put  down 
in  summary  form  the  conclusions  which  constitute  the  Idealism  of  his 
early  and  central  years ;  and  in  doing  this,  to  note  what  the  internal 
incompleteness,  just  referred  to,  is.  (2)  Then  to  turn  to  the  other 
side,  and  consider  the  operation  upon  Plato,  and  in  Plato,  of  the 
influences  that  lead  toward  Mysticism.  (3)  Finally,  to  consider  the 
later  stage  of  his  philosophy,  in  order  to  see  (a)  how  far  he  has  made 
good  the  incompleteness  of  his  earlier  Idealism,  (/?)  how  far  he  has 
overcome,  and  how  far  yielded  to,  the  influences  leading  him  toward 
Mysticism.  The  two  latter  questions,  it  will  be  noted,  do  not  stand 
apart;  they  are  so  closely  interconnected  as  really  to  form  one  ques 
tion  ;  for  the  more  clearly  and  fully  Plato  works  out  his  Idealism,  the 
more  completely  does  he  overcome  the  tendency  toward  Mysticism. 

First,  then,  from  the  dialogues  up  to  and  including  the  Republic, 
we  have  to  gather  the  ground-lines  of  the  earlier  Platonic  Idealism, 
and  to  set  these  down  in  the  form  of  a  brief  summary. 

I. 

What  Plato  saw  to  begin  with  was  that  our  experience,  our  actual 
present  life,  in  order  to  be  what  it  is,  must  be  a  part  in  a  system  of 
reality  greater  than  anything  that  now  appears  to  us.  He  saw — saw 
with  a  clearness  which  simply  startles  an  English  student  turning 
back  to  him  from  Locke  or  Bentham  or  the  Mills — that  there  is  in  our 
present  experience  something  which  this  present  world  cannot-  give ; 
that  there  operates  in  our  experience  something  which  that  experience 
itsel'f  as  it  now  stands  cannot  account  for.  For  our  experience  involves 
— one  might  almost  say,  is — the  operation  of  conceptions  which,  both 

208 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

in  perfection  and  in  universality,  go  beyond  the  particular  things  and 
facts  and  events  to  which  we  apply  them,  and  which  we  comprehend  by 
means  of  them.  They,  it  must  be  repeated,  are  not  merely  present  in 
our  experience ;  they  are  active  and  formative  in  it.  They  are  in  our 
minds  not  merely  as  something  possessed,  but  as  something  operative; 
operative  in  the  whole  process  of  our  thinking  and  knowing  and  doing. 
The  straight  line,  for  instance,  the  perfect  circle,  the  perfect  square, 
the  perfectly  equiangular  triangle — these  conceptions  and  the  many 
similar  ones  which  might  be  named,  are,  in  the  first  place,  actual 
possessions  of  our  minds;  but  not  that  only;  they  are  absolutely 
essential  to  even  the  most  elementary  process  of  knowing  the  world, 
and  in  that  process  are  continuously  operative  and  continuously  regu 
lative.  Yet  this  present  world  does  not  give  them;  there  are  no 
straight  lines  or  perfect  circles  in  nature.  And  again,  as  we  know 
nature,  so  also  we  regulate  our  conduct,  by  conceptions  which  the 
present  world  cannot  give  because  it  has  them  not  to  give.  We  seek 
perfect  truth,  and  justice  absolute,  and  the  courage  that  is  complete  in 
wisdom ;  but  where  are  these  to  be  found  existing  upon  the  earth  ? 

Here,  then,  in  the  elementary  facts  and  the  elementary  form  of  our 
scientific  and  moral  experience,  is  a  great  problem;  and  this  problem 
is  the  point  of  departure  for  that  great  voyage  of  the  intellect,  to  which 
Plato,  by  many  interests,  practical  even  more  than  speculative,  was 
driven.  As  he  advances  from  it,  he  works  his  way  to  a  view  of  what 
a  Greek  wmild  call  the  form — a  modern,  the  constitution  or  eternal 
order — of  the  world;  and  to  a  corresponding  view  of  the  place,  the 
development,  the  true  function,  of  the  soul  as  a  part  of  that  eternal 
world.  This  view  we  have  now  to  consider;  though,  as  we  go  on  to 
set  it  down  in  orderly  outline,  we  must  remember  that  Plato  himself 
nowhere  presents  it  in  one  systematically  articulated  account ;  for  it 
was  his  habit  to  develop  now  one,  now  another,  of  the  many  insights 
which  enter  into  it;  and  to  develop  these  single  insights,  moreover, 
by  the  method  which  best  corresponds  to  the  process  and  struggle  and 
gathering  light  of  actual  experience — the  dialectic  method. 

(1)  First,  then,  Plato  finds  the  form  or  constitution  of  the  world 
to  be  essentially  rational ;  this  is  the  keynote  of  his  Idealism,  and  of 
all  Idealism.  And  unless  Platonic  Idealism,  and  all  Idealism,  is  to  be 
15  209 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

radically  misapprehended,,  it  must  be  clearly  understood  what  it  means 
to  say  that  the  world  is  rational  in  its  constitution.  It  means  some 
thing  more  than  that  each  of  the  various  things  of  the  world  has 
independently  in  itself  a  rational  nature.  It  means  that  all  the  things 
of  the  world  form  one  rational  structure;  form  a  system  or  process  in 
which  reason  is  realised.  A  number  of  forms,  each  rational  in  the 
sense  of  being  apprehensible  by  reason,  but  simply  existing  side  by 
side,  would  not  constitute  a  rational  order.  A  rational  order  implies 
some  common  purpose,  some  supreme  principle,  which  is  realised  in 
and  through  the  total  system  or  structure.  That  principle  gives  to 
each  part  or  element  in  the  system  its  place  and  function,  and  by 
giving  to  it  its  place  and  function  gives  it  its  meaning  and  reality. 
So  that  the  principle  itself  is  at  once  the  immanent  law  and  con 
stitutive  energy — is  even,  in  a  sense,  the  essential  reality — of  the  whole 
system.  This  is  true  of  any  system,  of  any  whole  made  up  of  parts, 
which  is  to  be  called  rational.  Most  of  all  is  it  true  of  that  greatest  of  all 
"  ordered  and  organised  "  wholes  which  is  the  real  world.  If  the  real 
world  is  an  "  ordered  and  organised  whole,"  it  is  the  realisation  of  some 
one  supreme  principle,  which  is  at  once  the  source  and  the  immanent 
law  of  the  structure  of  the  world,  and  as  such  gives  to  each  of  those 
individual  forms  that  make  up  the  system  of  the  world,  its  place,  its 
function,  its  character,  its  reality.  This  principle  realised  and  fulfilled 
in  the  structure  of  the  world,  Plato,  in  accordance  with  Greek  usage, 
calls  the  Good.  To  him,  that  is  to  say,  the.  order  or  constitution  of 
the  world  consists  in  an  hierarchy  of  rational  forms — as  he  called 
them,  Ideas — with  the  Idea  of  Good  at  the  head  of  the  hierarchy.  Or, 
to  put  it  in  one  word,  the  Good,  as  the  source  and  law  of  all  individual 
determinations,  of  all  individual  capacities  and  functions,  and  thus  of 
all  individual  being,  is  the  principle  of  reality.1 

The  steps  in  Plato's  dialectic  advance  to  this  insight  were  of  course 
many.  One  of  them  we  shall  have  to  deal  with  later,  in  considering 
the  forces  that  broke  in  upon  Plato's  Idealism,  and  made  it  all  the 
greater  by  making  its  battle  harder.  Here,  however,  a  brief  hint  at 
the  general  course  of  this  part  of  the  Platonic  argument  will  be 

i  See  Philosophical  Lectures  and  Remains  of  Bichard  Lewis  Nettleship,  1st  ed.,  vol. 
II.,  pp.  217-237. 

210 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

sufficient.  First,  Plato  saw  that  particular  objects  cannot  stand  alone. 
Their  lack  of  an  abiding  form,  their  incessant  change,  their  .arising 
and  their  decay,  show  that  they  do  not  maintain  their  own  being  or 
exist  in  their  own  right.  How,  then,  are  they  to  be  accounted  for  ?  At 
the  very  lowest — making  your  first  concession  to  reason  as  small  as 
you  possibly  can — you  must  go  at  least  this  far :  that  for  each  of  the 
kinds,  for  each  group  of  similar  things,  there  must  be  some  one  abid 
ing  reality  which  fulfils  itself  through  them  and  their  changes.  This 
abiding  reality — to  which  Plato  gave  the  name  Idea — he,  at  the 
beginning  of  his  work,  tended  to  some  extent  to  view  as  the  common 
element  that  remained  when  the  differences  of  the  particulars  were 
stripped  away.  But  more  and  more  he  came  to  view  it  as  an  energetic 
principle,  a  creative  power,  which  manifests  itself  in  and  through  the 
things;  so  that  instead  of  our  being  compelled  to  abstract  from  the 
differences  to  get  it,  it  itself  explains  those  differences.  An  Idea 
might  perhaps  be  best  defined  for  the  modern  mind  by  saying  that 
each  Idea,  together  with  the  things  of  which  it  is  the  principle,  would 
form  the  object  of  a  special  science  or  special  department  of  science.1 
But  with  this  " lowest  possible  concession"  we  cannot  stop.  For 
these  constitutive  principles  of  the  various  classes  of  existence  cannot 
themselves  stand  apart  or  maintain  their  own  being.  They  are  not 
independent  existences,  standing  side  by  side  for  ever;  they  must  be 
conceived  as  forming  one  order,  one  universe.  And  what  that  means 
we  have  already  seen ;  they  are  the  media  or  organs  through  which  one 
highest  principle,  one  supreme  creative  energy,  the  Good,  fulfils  itself. 
(2)  The  nature  and  operative  principles  of  our  minds  correspond 
to  the  nature  and  operative  principles  of  the  world ;  'thus  it  is  that 
knowledge  and  intelligent  conduct  are  possible  to  us.  The  soul  which 
is  man,  is  in  organic  union  with  those  constitutive  principles  of  the 
world  (the  Ideas) — or,  if  you  will,  is  in  organic  possession  of  them. 
It  brings  them,  or  the  potentiality  of  them,  with  it  as  its  equipment 
for  the  business  of  life,  as  its  principles  of  knowledge  and  its  standards 
of  conduct.  This  insight  Plato  delighted  to  set  forth  in  myths  of 
unexampled  splendour.  But  the  meaning  of  the  myths  is  plain:  the 

i  E.  Caird,  Evolution  of  Theology  in  the  Greek  Philosophers,  vol.  I.,  p.  119  seq. 

211 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

real  world  is  rational;    the  soul  is  reason;    therefore,    science    and 
intelligent  conduct  are  alike  possible. 

(3)  But  that  nature  of  the  soul,  and  those  its  operative  principles, 
are  developed  only  gradually,  in  and  by  that  process  in  which  we  at 
once  apprehend  reality  and  come  to  be  ourselves.  In  knowing  the 
world,  the  reason  which  is  man,  recognising  the  presence  and  operation 
of  those  eternal  principles  in  the  world,  comes  more  and  more  into 
possession  of  them,  and  so  comes  more  and  more  truly  to  be  itself. 
This  apprehension  of  the  world,  in  its  gradual  development,  passes 
from  stage  to  stage  of  clearness;  passes,  as  Plato  at  one  point  says,1 
through  three  lower  stages  to  find  rest  in  a  fourth.  The  first  two  of 
these  (" conjecture"  and  "belief"),  which  represent  the  working  of 
the  intellect  below  the  "  scientific  "  level,  we  need  not  dwell  upon  here. 
But  we  must  notice  carefully  the  third,  and  the  transition  from  it  to 
the  fourth.  The  third  is  what  nowadays  we  should  call  the  stage  of 
the  special  sciences.  Its  defect  is  that  each  of  its  special  divisions  has 
its  own  point  of  view  and  its  own  point  of  departure ;  so  that  instead 
of  seeing  one  universe  in  the  light  of  one  supreme  principle,  it  almost 
has  several  universes.  Or,  as  one  may  put  it,  it  begins  too  far  down 
the  stream,  and  so,  instead  of  seeing  one  stream,  flowing  from  one 
fountainhead,  it  sees  only  several  different  currents.  At  this 
stage,  then,  knowledge  is  inaccurate  in  the  sense  of  being  abstract, 
"  unfinished,"  incomplete.  But  in  the  fourth  stage,  knowledge 
becomes  adequate  in  form  to  its  object.  For  here  knowledge 
directs  itself  to  that  supreme  principle,  only  in  the  light  of 
which  can  any  particular  thing  whatever  be  truly  understood; 
namely,  to  the  Good,  which  the  whole  system  and  structure  of  the 
universe  is  intended  to  realise,  and  which,  therefore,  determines  the 
place  and  function — that  is  to  say,  determines  the  reality — of  each 
individual  thing  in  the  total  system.  So  that  the  Good,  just  as  it  is 
the  principle  of  being,  is  also  the  principle  of  knowledge.  With 
regard  both  to  the  world  and  to  our  minds  it  is  the  principle  of  intel 
ligence;  for  it  is  its  activity,  as  giving  to  the  things  of  the  world 
•definite  determinations,  definite  places  in  the  system,  definite 
functions,  that  makes  the  things  of  the  world  intelligible;  and  it  is 

i  Republic,  509  D  seq. 
212 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OP    IDEALISM 

only  through  an  apprehension  of  it  that  our  minds  can  enter  fully  and 
finally  into  a  true  apprehension  of  things,  and  so  become  truly  and 
fully  intelligent.  Hence,  too,  knowledge  of  it  (and  conformity  of 
character  to  it)  is  the  ultimate  object  of  education;  and  it  is  in  the 
science  which  seeks  to  apprehend  it,  that  education — for  those  who  are 
able  to  go  so  far — culminates. 

(4)  To  live  in  accordance  with  that  true  nature  of  the  world  is 
the  true  way  of  life  for  men.  The  world,  as  a  system  in  which  a 
supreme  principle,  the  Good,  realises  itself  (in  measure  and  beauty 
and  truth,  as  Plato  said  later),1  furnishes  the  pattern  according  to 
which  man  should  organise  his  life.  Indeed  that  statement  is  too 
weak;  for  the  world  is  the  whole  in  which  man  lives;  so  that  the 
Good  which  is  the  organising  principle  of  its  structure  and  order, 
should  be  the  organising  principle  for  his  life.  That  is  to  say,  the 
Good  (that  which  the  world  exists  to  realise)  is  more  than  a  pattern 
for  man;  it  is  that  to  which  men  should  directly  devote  themselves 
and  seek  to  realise.  So  that  the  Good,  as  it  is  the  principle  of  being,  and 
the  principle  of  intelligence,  is  also  the  moral  end  for  man.  Moral 
ity  means  to  know  the  Good  which  is  the  eternal  law  of  the  world,  and 
to  make  it  the  supreme  principle  of  one's  own  life.  But  further :  men 
cannot  realise  the  Good  as  solitary  individuals.  They  must  become 
what  the  world  is — a  jcoffjuos,  an  "  ordered  and  organised  "  society, 
a  state.  The  state,  then,  is  a  human  institute  for  the  realisation  of 
the  Good.  In  accordance  with  that  purpose  and  no  other,  the  state 
is  to  frame  its  constitution,  to  train  its  citizens,  to  educate  its  legisla 
tors  and  statesmen ; — is  even  to  limit  its  own  size,  so  that  the  individ 
ual  citizen  shall  not  be  prevented  from  participating  in  the  whole  of  its 
life.  And  if  a  man  is  compelled  to  live  in  a  state  whose  constitution 
is  evil  or  imperfect,  let  him  organise  his  life  so  far  as  he  can  in 
accordance  with  the  order  of  the  city  whose  "  pattern  is  laid  up  in 
heaven";2  it  is  the  model  for  all  cities,  and  the  only  model  for  the 
man  whose  earthly  city  has  an  evil  constitution;  and,  after  death,  it 
will  receive  those  who  have  been  faithful  to  its  laws.3 

1  Philebus,  especially  64-67. 

2  Republic,  592. 

3  It  is  interesting  to  note  how  men's  thoughts  answer  one  another  across  the  ages. 
Plato  saw  that  our  experience,  in  order  to  be  what  it  now  is,  must  be  part  of  a  reality 

213 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

The  foregoing  statement  is  un-Platonic  in  form,  but  represents 
fairly,  in  terms  of  modern  thought,  the  essential  principles  that  had 
shaped  themselves  in  Plato's  mind  by  the  time  he  reached  middle  life. 
If  it  were  permissible  to  select  any  one  Platonic  statement  as  the  most 
pointed  expression  of  those  principles,  and  of  the  view  of  the  world 
which  they  constitute,  it  would  be  the  comparison,  in  the  Republic,  of 
i  the  Idea  of  Good  to  the  sun.  The  sun  is  to  visible  things  the  source 
both  of  their  being  and  of  their  visibility.  Of  their  being,  for  he 
makes  them  what  they  are ;  he  is  "  the  author  of  generation  and 
nourishment  and  growth,  though  he  himself  is  not  generation."  And 
of  their  visibility,  for  he  gives  to  them  their  capacity  of  being  seen 
and  to  the  eye  its  capacity  of  seeing  them.  In  the  same  way  the 
Idea  of  Good  gives  to  all  things  their  real  and  essential  existence ;  and, 
by  precisely  the  same  creative  or  constitutive  activity,  it  gives  to  them 
that  rational  character — that  place  in  a  rational  system  fulfilling  a 
rational  end — which  is  their  knowableness.1  The  Idea  of  Good, 
in  one  word,  is  the  principle  of  being,  the  principle  of  knowledge,  and, 
as  is  added  a  little  later,'2  the  principle  of  conduct. 

II. 

Such  a  view  concerning  the  form  or  constitution  of  the  world, 
and  concerning  the  place  and  development  and  function  of  the  soul  in 
the  world,  is  Idealism.  And  yet,  in  anything  that  can  be  called  a 
study  of  Plato,  this  view  must  stand  as  the  beginning  rather  than  as 
the  end.  In  philosophy,  battles  easily  won  are  usually  either  not 
worth  the  winning,  or  are  won  so  easily  because  of  the  hard  labour  of 
earlier  men.  And  Plato's  battle  was  far  from  easily  won.  He  fought 
over  nearly  the  whole  ground  of  philosophy ;  that  it  is,  in  fact,  which 
makes  him  at  once  so  deeply  instructive  and  so  infinitely  suggestive. 

greater  than  anything  that  now  appears  to  us ;  and  so  he  marked  out  a  course  of  lifelong 
education  to  lead  us  to  the  knowledge  of  that  eternal  reality,  and  called  us  to  "philosophy," 
i.e.,  to  a  life  of  political  and  speculative  activities  in  which  we  more  and  more  make  our 
society  and  ourselves  at  one  with  that  reality.  It  is  precisely  the  same  insight—  or  one 
aspect  of  it— that  Professor  Royce  (The  World  and  the  Individual,  First  Series,  p.  56)  puts 
into  the  terse  statement :  "  We  live  looking  for  the  whole  of  our  meaning.  And  this 
looking  constitutes  the  process  called  thinking." 

i  507  seq.  2  5170. 

214 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

First,  as  was  pointed  out  above,  in  the  Idealism  whose  main 
positions  have  just  been  set  down,  there  is  a  certain  incompleteness. 
It  is  incomplete  in  the  conception  of  its  highest  principle.  For  it 
viewed  the  Idea  of  Good  as  a  constitutive  and  organising  principle. 
The 'Good  exercises  a  creative  energy;  it  is  the  source  and  home,  the 
ordering  power,  the  principle  of  unity,  of  the  world.  But  that  at  once 
raises  the  question :  In  order  to  be  such  a  principle,  must  not  the  Good 
be  conceived  as  something  more  than  simply  the  Good?  If  it  is  truly 
to  be  regarded  as  performing  the  supreme  function  of  constituting 
and  ordering  the  world,  must  it  not  be  taken  up  into  some  still  higher 
principle?  Must  it  not,  that  is  to  say,  be  regarded  as  living  and 
active  spirit;  so  that  the  world  would  be  viewed  as  constituted  by  an 
eternal  spirit  who  is  the  subject  of  the  world,  whose  Ideas  are  the 
regulative  forms  of  the  world,  and  the  supreme  law  of  whose  activity 
is  the  Good? 

To  this  problem  Plato  came  in  his  later  work.  In  that  work  he 
made,  indeed,  what  looks  like  a  fresh  start ;  for  he  came  at  the  problem 
from  a  somewhat  different  angle  of  approach,  and  used  a  different 
terminology.  But  really  it  is  the  same  problem ;  and  really,  therefore, 
the  advance  is  continuous.1  But  before  we  go  on  to  consider  that 
advance,  there  is  another  matter  to  be  dealt  with.  For,  as  also  was 
noted  above,  throughout  the  whole  of  Plato's  life,  the  forces  that  lead 
men,  not  to  Idealism  at  all,  but  to  Mysticism,  worked  upon  him ;  and 
upon  that  many-sided  mind,  sensitive  as  it  was  to  all  spiritual  influ 
ences,  they  could  not  be  without  effect.  To  these  we  must  now  turn ; 
and  in  dealing  with  them  we  have  to  consider  (A)  in  what  form  they 
acted  upon  Plato;  (B)  what  influence  they  had,  whether  in  breaking 
the  unity  and  preventing  the  completeness  of  his  Idealism,  or  in 
setting  another  view  alongside  of  it.  Then,  finally,  we  can  come  to 
that  thinking  of  his  later  years  in  which,  so  far  as  was  possible  to  him, 
he  dealt  with  both  the  great  problems  that  beset  him;  and,  by  a 
certain  development  of  his  thought,  at  once  put  the  keystone  into  the 
arch  of  his  Idealism,  and  overcame — though  to  the  end  only  in  part — 
the  mystic  tendency. 

1  One  of  the  reasons  for  believing — what  here  is  taken  for  granted— that  the  Parrncnidcs 
(with  the  allied  dialogues),  is  a  genuine  Platonic  writing. 

215 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

(A)  First,  then,  the  influences  that  make  for  Mysticism  fall  into 
two  great  classes.  For  Mysticism  has  a  twofold  aspect.  It  is  a  type 
of  speculative  thought;  but  it  is  also  a  movement  of  the  practical 
spirit.  It  is  an  intellectual  conclusion;  but  usually  it  is  also  a  con 
ception  of  religion  and  a  way  of  life. 

(1)  So  that  we  have  to  distinguish,  first,  the  more  purely  intel 
lectual  ways  along  which  men  are  led  to  Mysticism.  The  general 
tendency  manifest  in  these  may  be  seen  by  considering  the  situation 
in  which  the  philosophic  intellect  stands  at  the  beginning  of  its  work. 
For  what  sets  it  upon  its  work  is  the  insight  that  experience  can  be 
what  it  now  is  only  upon  the  supposition  that  reality  goes  far  beyond 
the  appearances  which  from  moment  to  moment  make  up  the  fleeting 
content  of  experience.  And  the  work  to  which  this  insight  calls 
philosophy  is,  of  course,  the  attempt  to  reach  a  form  of  consciousness 
more  adequate  than  the  everyday  consciousness  to  the  apprehension  of 
that  reality.  But  precisely  in  this  beginning  and  in  this  point  of 
departure  there  lies  for  the  intellect  a  great  danger.  It  should 
remember  that  the  reality  to  which  it  is  attempting  to  make  its  way,  is 
sought  as  the  explanation  and  the  illumination  of  the  experience  from 
which  it  first  set  out.  Or,  in  technical  terms,  it  should  remember  that 
the  desired  universal  and  the  present  particulars  are  in  organic  con 
nexion;  that  the  noumenal  order  does  not  stand  separate  from  time 
and  from  phenomena,  but  rather  is  the  phenomenal  order  truly  under 
stood  ;  else  the  one  is  no  explanation  of  the  other.  But  this  very  thing 
the  intellect  is  tempted,  not  to  say  driven,  to  forget ;  and  that  by  the 
nature  of  the  situation  itself.  For  wriaT"the  mind  is  seeking  to  do  is 
to  pass  from  an  experience  of  appearances  to  a  consciousness  of 
reality ;  and  what  stands  out  in  the  foreground,  and  is  acutely  felt,  is, 
of  course,  not  the  likeness  of  the  two,  but  tfreir  difference.  The 
reality — in  its  character  surely  it  is  that  which  the  appearances  are 
not.  They  come  and  go,  arise  and  decay;  it  abides  for  ever,  and  is 
always  itself.  They  are  chained  to  eye  and  ear;  it,  for  its  existence 
and  perfection,  depends  upon  no  perishing  organs  of  flesh.  Thus  the 
tendency  arises  to  separate  the  two :  what  they  are,  it  is  not ;  what  it 
is,  they  are  not.  And  the  two  being  separated,"  the  way  of  the  soul  is 

216 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

plain;  in  the  vision  of  the  perfect  and  eternal  reality,  it  must  forget, 
or  resist,  or  despise,  the  present  world. 

This  tendency  takes  many  forms  and  operates  in  many  degrees  of 
power.  A  number  of  the  purer  cases  of  it  we  have  already  considered 
in  dealing  with  Spinoza.1  It  did  its  work  almost  completely,  for 
instance,  when,  through  generations  of  forgotten  men,  the  Hindu 
mind,  moving  under  a  burden  of  sad  experience,  sought  to  reach  the 
one  fundamental  reality  by  saying  Neti,  Neti — It  is  not  so,  it  is  not  so 
— to  every  particular  form  of  god  or  goddess  and  to  every  particular 
natural  determination;  and  thus  accomplished  the  vast  march  of 
thought  from  Veda  to  Vedanta.  Or  again,  it  swept  in  perfect  intel 
lectual  clearness,  and  with  one  arrow-like  flight,  to  its  goal,  when  Par- 
menides  sharply  and  abruptly  set  over  against  the  world  of  the  senses, 
a  reality  which  purely  and  absolutely  is,  and  is  not  flawed  or  limited 
or  contaminated  by  any  "is  not."  These  thoroughgoing  cases,  as  a 
rule,  occur  either  at  the  beginning  of  a  great  civilisation,  or  in  its 
decline :  at  the  beginning,  when  the  pioneers  of  thought,  by  sheer 
force  of  speculative  daring,  carry  one-sided  methods  through  to  their 
conclusion ;  in  the  decline,  when  men  turn  away  from  the  evil  world, 
and  the  religious  influences  which  we  are  to  consider  in  a  moment  work 
victoriously  upon  them.  But  the  logic  of  Mysticism  is  also  able  to 
secure  a  footing  in  the  middle  periods,  when  the  great  constructive 
and  comprehensive  minds  are  at  work.  In  a  different  way,  however; 
usually  as  .a  tendency  concealed  in  some  method  which  is  accepted 
without  question,  but  whose  final  significance  is  not  perceived.  In 
such  a  method  Mysticism  often  lies  implicit,  until  at  last  some  intellect, 
fearless  in  its  logic,  but  working  in  the  service  of  the  religious  instinct, 
carries  the  method  relentlessly  to  its  conclusion,  and  shows  reality  to 
men  as  that  with  which  they  can  enter  into  union  only  by  renouncing 
the  world  and  all  the  normal  forms  of  experience. 

For  our  present  purpose,  one  such  method  is  specially  important. 
It  is,  indeed,  simply  a  particular  case  of  the  general  situation  described 
a  moment  ago.  The  facts  and  events  of  the  world,  as  they  are  given 
to  us  in  our  everyday  consciousness,  cannot  stand  alone.  If  we  would 
really  understand  them,  we  must  go  to  something  wider  than  them- 

i  Supra,  pp.  126-150. 
217 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

selves ;  to  the  laws  or  principles  which  govern  them,  which  hold  them 
together  and  make  them  and  their  changes  one  connected  and 
systematic  world.  In  the  language  of  philosophy,  we  must  go  to  their 
universals.  But  how  are  we  to  conceive  those  universals?  If  we 
remembered  that  we  seek  the  universal  as  an  explanation  of  the  par 
ticular,  we  should  see  that  the  universals  must  be  active  principles  of 
synthesis — active  and  concrete  principles  which  hold  things  together 
into  one  world,  and  by  giving  to  each  particular  its  place  in  the  world 
give  it  its  reality.  The  universals,  that  is  to  say,  would  be  conceived 
as  at  once  explaining  and  containing  both  the  particulars  and  their 
differences  and  their  relations;  would  be  conceived  as  at  once  the 
source  and  the  home  alike  of  the  particulars,  and  of  the  relations 
which  link  them  together  into  one  system,  and  of  the  differences  whicn 
mark  their  individuality.  And  the  highest  universal  would  be  the 
most  concrete  of  all,  being  the  source  and  home  of  the  whole  order  of 
the  world,  of  all  the  individuals  in  it,  and  of  all  the  relations  and  dif 
ferences  which  make  them  individuals  and  yet  link  them  together  by 
eternal  laws  in  the  one  system  of  the  world.  But  at  the  very  beginning 
of  the  search  for  universals  there  is  something  which  frequently  leads 
us  to  forget  all  this.  For  the  universal  is  something  which  is  common 
to  all  the  members  of  a  class ;  they  all  share  in  it,  and  their  sharing  in 
it  is  the  source  of  their  reality.  But  how  are  we  to  get  at  something 
which  is  common  to  all  the  diverse  members  of  a  class  ?  Surely  nothing 
can  be  easier — simply  strip  away  the  differences  and  retain  what  is 
left.  It  is  very  natural  thus  to  take  for  granted  that  since  the  universal 
is  a  form  common  to  all  the  members  of  a  class,  the  way  to  reach  it 
must  be  by  abstracting  from  the  differences  of  those  members.  But 
natural  as  it  is  to  drift  into  such  a  method,  it  puts  you,  as  soon  as  you 
adopt  it,  into  the  grip  of  the  logic  of  denial.  For  as  you  ascend  from 
stage  to  stage,  stripping  away  the  differences  from  particular  things 
and  specific  conceptions,  your  universals  become  more  and  more 
abstract,  until  at  last  you  reach  the  end  with  an  ineffable  One  which  is 
beyond  all  natural  determinations  and  all  forms  of  reason ;  and  union 
with  which,  whether  speculative  or  practical,1  is  therefore  to  be  attained 

i  Whether  speculative  or  practical : — To  the    thoroughgoing   Mystic,  it   should   be 
remembered,  these  are  really  one. 

218 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

only  in  some  experience  which  transcends  all  forms  of  reason  and  all 
ordinary  activities  of  the  rational  spirit  which  is  man.  Thus  it  was, 
for  instance,  that  mediaeval  Eealism  with  its  strong  tendency  to  ascend 
to  the  universal  by  the  method  of  abstraction,  led  the  way  to  Mysti 
cism.  When  its  method  was  taken  up  by  men  of  deep  inward  religion 
and  of  an  unflinching  logic  which  not  even  canons  and  decretals  could 
bind,  that  which  was  left  to  them  at  the  end,  after  they  had  abstracted 
from  the  last  differences — from  the  distinction  between  God  the 
omniscient  knower,  and  the  world,  ideal  or  temporal,  which  He  consti 
tutes  and  knows ;  and  from  the  distinction  between  the  persons  of  the 
Trinity — was  that  ultimate  Godhead,  that  "  still  wilderness  "  which 
"  never  did  look  upon  deed  "  and  "  where  never  was  seen  difference, 
neither  Father,  nor  Son,  nor  Holy  Ghost."1  The  same  tendency,  again, 
was  manifest  when  Spinoza,  on  one  side  of  his  thinking,  carried  to 
the  last  conclusion  a  method  and  a  principle  which,  coming  from 
Descartes,  seemed  new,  but  in  truth  were  as  old  as  mediaeval  Eealism, 
and  in  the  hands  of  a  rigorous  logician  had  in  them  the  same 
potentiality  of  Mysticism.  Or,  to  take  an  instance  which  lies  at  our 
very  doors,  the  abstract  tendency  is  present  in  the  later  thinking  of 
Kant,  and  is  in  constant  strife  with  that  concrete  or  synthetic  method 
which  is  Kant's  proper  contribution  to  modern  philosophy;  a  strife 
so  continuous  that  without  reference  to  it,  as  the  Master  of  Balliol  in 
almost  every  chapter  of  his  great  exposition  has  to  remind  us,  scarcely 
any  leading  point  in  Kant's  critical  philosophy  can  be  understood.2 

1  See  the  paper  on  Meister  Eckhart  in  Professor  Royce's  Studies  of  Good  and  Evil ; 
especially  pp.  276-282,  and  the  words  of  Sch wester  Katrei  as  given  on  p.  297. 

2  Indeed,  it  might  almost  be  said  that  in  man's  effort  to  come  to  reality,  Mysticism 
may  arise  from  any  important  error,  from  any  important  misuse  of  categories,  provided 
(1)  that  the  method  employed  be  that  of  the  purely  analytic  logic  which  carries  a  beginning 
rigorously  to  the  conclusion,  allowing  no  opportunity  for  turning  back  upon  it  to  criticise 
or  reconstitute  it ;  (2)  that  the  men  be  too  completely  possessed  by  intellectual  gravity  or 
by  religious  passion  to  rest  in  the  philosophic  scepticism  which  would  be  the  outcome  of 
the  mere  logic  of  the  situation.    To  take  a  most  unpromising  instance — a  case  where  the 
beginning  augurs  anything  but  a  mystic  close— if  a  man,  deeply  religious  but  at  the  same 
time  keenly  logical,  were  with  implicit  confidence  to  accept  as  his  point  of  departure 
almost  any  book  of   the  traditional  English  or  Scottish  school  of  philosophy,  he  would 
almost  certainly  become  a  Mystic ;  would  almost  certainly  come  to  deny  the  world  given 
to  his  present  intelligence  in  the  name  of  a  reality  not  apprehensible  by  intelligence,  and 
to  seek  desperately  for  some  way  of  union  with  that  reality.  Indeed,  if  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer, 
retaining  his  philosophy,  had  been  predominantly  a  man  of  religion  rather  than  predomin 
antly  a  man  of  science,  he  would  have  been  a  Mystic. — But  the  most  remarkable  of  recent 

219 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

In  Plato  both  that  general  and  this  special  form  of  the  intellectual 
movement  toward  Mysticism  are  found.  The  explanation  of  our 
present  world  and  of  our  experience  in  it,  lies  for  him  in  a  world  of 
perfect  and  eternal  realities),  the  Ideas,  which  are  at  once  rational 
forms  and  rational  energies.  And,  of  course,  he  knew  that  the  explana 
tion  and  the  thing  explained  must  be  in  organic  union:  that  world, 
he  knew,  must  be  the  truth  of  this  world;  this  world,  truly  known, 
must  be  a  factor  or  element  in  the  life  of  that,  and  a  manifestation  of 
its  nature.  But,  like  all  high  and  clear  spirits  who  are  acutely  sensi 
tive  to  the  evil  and  the  imperfection  of  this  world,  Plato  is  tempted  to 
let  his  soul  dwell  in  that  world,  forgetting  this,  or  despising  it,  or 
renouncing  it,  as  a  thing  only  of  some  secondary  reality  which  in  the 
presence  of  true  reality  stands  condemned  for  ever.  And  to  this 
temptation  to  set  the  two  worlds  apart,  the  one  as  shadow,  the  other 
as  reality,  he  continually  yields.  Perhaps  his  keenest  feeling  is  the 
feeling  of  the  difference  between  the  real  world  and  this  present  world 
of  the  senses — this,  inconstant,  fleeting,  full  of  change  and  decay; 
that,  with  its  unchanging  perfections  of  reason.  And  this  feeling,  as 
we  are  to  see  in  a  moment,  was  intensified  by  the  form  which  the 
religious  passion  often  took  in  him;  and  by  the  way  in  which  he 
suffered  from  the  resistance  of  his  Greek  world  to  that  ideal  which 
represents  the  demand  of  the  real  world  upon  present  society.  So  that, 
in  his  central  period,  Plato,  like  Erigena,  like  Aquinas,  like  Spinoza, 
like  Kant — like  his  own  pupil,  Aristotle — is  torn  between  the  synthetic 
and  the  abstract  movements  of  thought,  between  theologia  affirmativa 
and  theologia  negativa.  It  is  true  that  the  conflict  of  these  tendencies 
assumed  a  very  different  form  in  him  from  that  which  it  assumed  in 
Erigena  or  Aquinas,  in  Spinoza  or  Kant.  It  is  true  also  that  the 
yielding  to  the  negative  tendency  is  less  in  him  than  in  any  of  the 
others  just  named;1  true  that  the  promise  and  the  power  of  that 
thoroughgoing  Idealism  to  which  he  was  later  to  come  is  already  in 

intellectual  approaches  to  Mysticism  comes  from  a  very  different  direction.  It  is  (if  I  may 
venture  so  daring  a  statement)  that  found  in  the  keenest  of  modern  English  dialecticians, 
a  man  of  thought  to  whom  we  are  all  deeply  indebted,  Mr.  F.  H.  Bradley.  The  cause  of 
it,  which  lies  in  his  treatment  of  some  of  the  higher  categories,  is  most  interesting  but 
cannot  be  discussed  here. 

i  Even  than  in  Aristotle,    See  the  discussion  in  Caird,  Evolution  of  Theology  in  the 
Greek  Philosophers,  vol.  I.,  especially  pp.  285,  286. 

220 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

the  dialogues  of  the  central  period.  But  none  the  less  the  strife  is 
there.  And  in  the  special  form  mentioned  an  instant  ago — i.e.,  in 
advancing  from  particulars  to  class-conceptions — the  strife  is  also 
there.  In  the  earlier  thinking  of  Plato  there  is  a  wavering  between 
two  views  of  the  relation  of  a  universal  to  the  particulars  grouped 
under  it ;  the  two  views,  as  one  may  say,  are  present  in  solution.  The 
one,  regarding  the  universal  as  the  common  element  in  different 
individuals,  tends  to  seek  it  by  abstraction,  by  leaving  aside  the  differ 
ences  of  those  individuals,  and  to  give  it  an  existence  independent  and 
separate ;  making  it,  to  use  an  expression  of  the  later  Plato,  like  a  sail 
drawn  over  the  individual  members  of  the  class.1  The  other  regards  it 
as  a  synthetic  principle,  manifesting  itself  through  differences,  and 
therefore  both  explaining  and  containing  those  differences.  And  as  far 
as  the  former  prevails,  it  makes  possible,  in  the  way  already  indicated, 
the  logic  of  Mysticism. 

(2)  But,  as  we  have  seen,  there  is  another  order  of  influences 
making  for  Mysticism — the  practical  or  religious ;  and  it  is  only  when 
these  co-operate  with  the  first  that  Mysticism  in  the  completeness  of 
its  type  arises.  The  nature  of  these  may  be  indicated  in  this  way. — To 
the  religious  instinct  and  passion,  in  its  higher  development,  two 
directions  of  movement  are  possible;  and  thus  in  man's  effort  after 
God  two  tendencies  have  arisen.  These  are  seldom  found  in  purity  of 
type,  ordinary  religious  life  usually  containing  both,  though  approx 
imating  sometimes  to  the  one,  sometimes  to  the  other.  Of  these 
tendencies  the  one  which  commonly  is  the  earlier  to  prevail,  whether 
in  the  individual  or  in  any  deeply  religious  age,  is  dominated  by  the 
sense  of  the  sharp  contrast  between  the  world  and  God;  the  world  as 
evil,  God  as  altogether  good;  or  the  world  as  nothingness  and  vanity, 
God  as  all  in  all.  But  the  later  and  more  thoughtful  tendency  sees 
that  Manichseism  in  any  form  shatters  religion  itself;  that  the 
religious  life  in  its  every  step  implies  .an  organic  connexion  between 
God  and  the  world;  God  being  led  by  the  goodness  of  His  nature  to 
impart  Himself;  the  world  being  a  process  wherein,  by  that  increas 
ing  impartation  of  Himself,  He  realises  an  eternal  purpose  which 
itself  arises  from  His  nature  and  is  the  expression  of  it.  The  religion 

1  Parmenides,  131  BC. 
221 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

of  this  latter  type  is  the  wider  and  the  prof  (Hinder ;  in  a  certain  very 
important  sense,  it  is  really  the  more  religious.  But  the  religion  of  the 
former  kind  is  usually  the  more  intense  and  overmastering.  It  makes 
ascetics  and  warriors;  and  it  has  in  it  at  least  the  beginning  of 
Mysticism.  For  on  the  one  hand  it  presupposes  an  eternal  reality  and 
the  possibility  that  man  can  become  at  one  with  it;  and  it  makes  the 
quest  after  such  union  the  supreme  business  of  life.  But  on  the  other 
hand  it  is  convinced  that  upon  no  such  ways  as  those  of  the  present 
world,  through  no  such  energies  as  those  of  man's  natural  soul,  is  that 
union  to  be  attained. 

Now,  Plato  was  a  man  profoundly  religious.  And  both  his  native 
character  and  the  circumstances  of  his  life  made  it  inevitable  that  at 
least  occasionally,  under  special  stress  of  the  world's  evil  or  the  world's 
tragedy,  the  religious  temper  in  him  should  assume  the  first  rather 
than  the  second  of  the  two  forms  just  distinguished.  For  in  him  was 
the  grave  Dorian  austerity  which  can  lift  men  with  indignant  scorn 
above  the  allurements  of  the  world;  and  the  hunger  after  eternity 
and  after  perfection,  which  in  this  world,  or  in  any  world  made  after 
the  fashion  of  this,  can  find  no  rest;  and  that  inborn  purity  of  mind, 
observable  in  fine  and  high  spirits,  which  turns  instinctively  away 
from  evil  and  seeks  its  home  with  a  reality  in  which  evil  and  the 
trouble  of  evil  have  no  place.  And  his  outer  life  was  fitted  to  develop 
the  world-denying  instincts  within.  Only  too  well  he  knew  the  sadden 
ing  of  the  soul  which  comes  to  men  who  enter  upon  life  with  high 
devotion  to  the  welfare  of  their  society  .and  to  the  great  causes  in 
which  that  welfare  consists,  and  find  the  world  to  be  a  body  of  death, 
immovable  by  that  passion,  unresponsive  to  those  purposes.  It  was 
not  merely  that  the  men  of  Athens,  the  best  of  them  as  well  as  the 
worst,  had  slain  his  master.  But  in  him  a  high  ethical  and  political 
passion,  the  passion  of  the  reformer  who  has  gazed  upon  heavenly 
perfection  and  seeks  to  bring  it  to  the  ways  of  earthly  society,  broke 
in  vain  against  the  life  of  his  day ;  broke  in  vain  against  the  pride  of 
the  elder  Dionysius;  in  vain  against  the  life  of  Athens,  where  the 
citizens  were  no  longer  men  of  Marathon,  but  loved  comfort  and 
cleverness  and  unstable  change  more  than  righteousness;  in  vain 
against  the  general  political  condition  of  the  Greek  world  in  the  period 

222 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

that  runs  from  the  day  of  the  Thirty  to  the  coming  of  the  Macedonian. 
And  so  it  came  to  pass  that  through  the  whole  course  of  Plato's  life 
there  ran  that  same  tragedy  of  passion  and  of  hope  which  filled  the 
early  years  of  Wordsworth.  The  passion  of  the  prophet  and  of  the 
reformer  shattered  itself  into  despair  against  the  circumstances  of  the 
age,  and  against  the  brute  power  with  which  political  inefficiency  and 
political  corruption  can  maintain  themselves  against  high  ideals  and 
high  character.1 

(B)  Thus,  then,  the  influences  that  lead  toward  the  doctrine  and 
life  of  the  Mystics,  acted  upon  the  founder  himself  of  Idealism.  What 
response,  we  must  next  ask,  did  they  call  forth  ?  what  result  had  they 
in  Plato's  view  of  reality  and  of  the  way  of  life  ? 

One  thing  is  clear  to  begin  with.  They  have  influenced  very  deeply 
the  tone  and  expression  of  the  Platonic  philosophy.  It  presents  itself 
to  its  students  as  a  many-coloured  web  shot  through  and  through  with 
mystic  motives.  Not  only  toward  what  we  commonly  call  the  things 
of  the  world,  but  also  toward  many  even  of  the  virtues  in  their 
ordinary  exercise,  and  toward  the  opinion  which  is  at  least  a  poten 
tiality  of  knowledge,  and  toward  many  of  the  greater  literary  and 
artistic  forms,  Plato  takes  up  frequently  the  true  Mystic's  attitude  of 
pity  and  renunciation  and  rebuke.  And  he  has  the  Mystic's  strange 
and  compelling  glory  of  speech,  the  power  mingled  of  prophecy  and 
poetry,  which,  logically  or  illogically,  has  fallen  so  often  to  the  lot  of 
those  who  use  speech  only  for  winning  men  to  the  silent  life.  In  calling 
men  to  the  renunciation  of  the  world,  to  the  practice  of  death,  his 
words  take  on  the  tint  of  Mysticism,  just  as  sometimes,  on  evenings 
late  in  autumn,  the  sky  that  bent  over  the  work  of  the  day  ceases  to  be 
a  thing  of  this  world,  and  with  stern  magnificence  and  yet  with  beauty 
unutterable  testifies  against  the  weariness  and  the  ambitions  of  the 
earth,  and  against  the  men  who  in  these  things  lose  themselves. 

Nevertheless,  the  outcome  in  Plato  was  not  Mysticism.  It  was  not 
to  be  that  among  men  of  Greek  speech  the  great  argument  which  Par- 
menides  had  left  a  thing  purely  intellectual  should  advance  to  "  do  the 
full  work  of  a  philosophy"  as  an  ethic  and  a  religion.  Though  Plato 

i  See  the  excellent  statement  in  Windelband,  Platon,  especially  in  the  first  chapter 
and  in  the  concluding  pages. 

223 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

revered  Parmenid.es,  and  though  of  all  the  Hellenes  he  was  the  most 
fitted  in  character  and  experience  to  respond  to  the  appeal  of  Mysti 
cism,  yet  the  very  fact  that  he  was  a  Hellene  made  it  impossible  that 
it  should  be  his  vocation  to  lift  the  Parmenidean  view  of  reality  into 
a  wisdom  for  the  guidance  of  life,  and  to  give  to  that  wisdom  its 
language  of  irresistible  persuasion.  The  Greek  loyalty  to  reason  and 
the  energies  of  reason;  the  Greek  love  of  definite  and  specific  form; 
the  Greek  belief  that  such  form  is  truly  and  essentially  characteristic 
of  reality : — these  held  the  field.  He  was  not  won  away  from  his  view 
that  the  forms  and  energies  which  constitute  reality  are  forms  and 
energies  of  reason ;  and  that  this  rationality  of  the  real  means  that  it 
has  one  supreme  and  organising  principle,  the  Good,  without  devotion 
to  which  reason  is  not  reason.  And  holding  to  this,  he  is  not  a 
Mystic.  For  though  he  may  sometimes  speak  of  the  present  world 
with  the  voice  of  a  Mystic,  yet  there  remains  a  difference  which  is 
essential.  The  relation  between  Plato  when  he  goes  farthest  toward 
Mysticism,  and  the  thoroughgoing  Mystic,  might  be  stated  in  this 
way. — Both  believe  that  there  is  a  reality  untroubled  by  change  or  evil 
or  decay.  Both  believe  that  in  union  with  that  reality  lies  the  welfare 
and  blessedness  of  the  soul.  Both  believe  that  it  is  beyond  all  reach  of 
sense-perception.  But  the  Mystic  goes  on  to  add  that  it  lies  just  as 
much  beyond  all  forms  of  reason  as  it  does  beyond  sense-perception,  so 
that  if  you  would  apprehend  it,  and  make  it  your  own,  and  become  at 
one  with  it,  it  must  be  in  an  immediacy  of  experience  which  transcends 
reason,  transcends  all  ordinary  forms  of  cognitive  and  moral  experi 
ence.  While  Plato  urges,  on  the  contrary,  that  the  truly  real  is  the 
very  perfection  of  reason,  the  very  perfection  of  all  rational  form  and 
rational  energy,  and  that  it  is  by  perfecting  the  reason  within  you — 
reason  in  the  greater  sense  of  the  word,  not  the  mere  logical  intellect — 
that  you  draw  near  to  it.  With  the  Mystic,  to  put  it  in  a  word,  the 
negatives  directed  against  the  present  world,  and  against  the  life  that 
men  live  if  they  walk  in  its  ways,  are  uttered  in  the  name  of  a  reality 
above  reason ;  with  Plato  those  same  negatives  are  uttered  in  the  name 
of  a  reality  which  is  the  completeness  of  reason. 

So  that  Plato,  even  though  you  can  learn  a  great  deal  of  practical 
Mysticism  from  him  if  you  have  the  right   kind  of  soul,  remains  an 

224 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

Idealist.  Yet  the  influences  which  we  have  been  considering  were  by 
no  means  without  their  effect.  They  were  not  able  to  make  the  earlier 
Plato  a  Mystic.  But  they  were  able  to  do  something :  they  were  able 
to  determine  the  type  of  his  Idealism.  They  caused  it  to  be  of  that 
modified  type  which  was  sketched  on  an  earlier  page,1  under  the  name 
of  Abstract  Idealism :  that  which  regards  the  genuine  reality  and  the 
true  home  of  the  soul  as  a  world  of  pure  reason  (in  that  larger  sense  of 
the  word  already  indicated),  from  which  this  present  world  of  the 
senses  is  separated  as  a  realm  of  merely  secondary  reality;  so  that 
the  union  of  the  soul  with  the  genuine  reality  is  to  be  won,  its  citizen 
ship  in  that  world  accomplished,  only  by  a  life  in  which  sense-experi 
ence  is  not  an  integral  element  subserving  the  interests  of  the  spirit, 
but  is  regarded  rather  as  an  alien  atmosphere  to  be  escaped  from. 

In  setting  down  the  broad  outlines  of  the  earlier  Platonic  Idealism 
we  noted  as  a  matter  of  fact,  and  without  considering  the  explanation, 
that  there  was  an  incompleteness  in  its  conception  of  its  highest  prin 
ciple.  What  we  have  now  seen  might  almost  be  put  in  this  way :  that 
corresponding  to  that  incompleteness  at  the  top,  there  is  an  incom 
pleteness  at  the  bottom;  the  world  given  to  the  senses  is  not  clearly 
and  unwaveringly  viewed  as  a  manifestation  of  the  highest  principle, 
and  as  a  factor  in  its  realisation  of  its  purpose. 

This,  however,  we  must  understand  somewhat  more  fully.  And 
that  can  best  be  done  by  returning  to  that  summary  outline,  and  con 
sidering  in  what  way  the  negative  tendency,  when  it  comes  to  the  front, 
is  able  to  modify  each  of  the  four  positions  there  indicated. 

(1)  First,  then,  Plato  often  speaks  as  if  the  system  of  Ideas  were 
not  so  much  the  form,  or  order,  or  constitution,  of  the  one  universe 
which  we  know  and  of  which  our  present  experience  is  an  integral 
part;  but  were  rather  a  universe  existing  by  itself  and  complete  in 
itself — the  real  universe;  and  this  sensible  and  temporal  process  in 
which  we  now  live,  a  system  having  only  a  secondary  reality.  So  that, 
in  this  aspect  of  Plato's  thought,  we  approach  to  a  theory  of  two 
worlds:  one  of  absolutely  pure  reason  and  complete  righteousness, 
where  without  hindrance  the  Good  perfectly  realises  itself ;  the  other 
an  imperfect  realm  of  sense  and  time.  And  of  this  lower  world  Plato 

i  Supra,  p.  12. 
16  225 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

speaks  in  varying  tones.  Sometimes  he  makes  it  a  shadow,  or  a 
hindrance,  or  a  prison.  From  it  the  good  man  seeks  to  escape, 
philosophy  as  a  "  practice  of  death  "  being  his  way  of  deliverance. 
At  other  times  he  views  it  as  in  some  sense  organically  connected 
with  the  world  of  Ideas.  The  things  of  this  world  have  some  share,  by 
participation  or  imitation  or  however  it  be,  in  the  nature  of  the  Ideas ; 
so  that  in  this  world,  even  in  the  forms  and  activities  of  the  "  unex- 
amined  life,"1  some  fulfilment  is  possible  of  that  Idea  which  is  the 
life-giving  sun  of  the  real  world — the  Good. 

(2)  But  when  Plato  has  to  deal  explicitly  with  the  question  of  the 
possibility  of  knowledge,  what  will  he  do  with  his  tendency  toward  a 
two-world  theory?  For  in  knowledge  the  two  worlds  are  together; 
particular  and  universal  .are  in  organic  connexion.  Knowledge  is 
really  an  interpreting  of  particulars  in  the  light  of  their  universals. 
Or,  if  you  have  failed  to  see  that,  and  regard  knowledge  as  having  to 
do  only  with  universals — so  that  the  process  of  gaining  knowledge  is 
a  passing  out  of  particulars  to  universals — still  the  very  fact  that  you 
can  pass  from,  the  one  to  the  other  shows  that  the  two  are  in  connexion. 
What  Plato  does  is  very  remarkable.  He  maintains — to  explain  the 
possibility  of  knowledge  he  must  maintain — his  belief  in  the  corre 
spondence  of  the  nature  and  principles  of  our  minds  to  the  nature  and 
principles  of  reality,  and  in  the  consequent  capacity  of  our  minds  to 
form  class-conceptions  which  represent  to  us  the  Ideas.  But  when 
his  sense  of  the  gulf  between  the  two  worlds  is  strong  upon  him,  he 
expresses  that  belief  not  scientifically,  but  prophetically,  in  myths  and 
parables  that  for  blended  charm  and  majesty  stand  unequalled  in 
literature.  (The  souls  of  men — so  in  these  he  teaches — pre-existed,  and 
in  their  pre-existence  gained  some  glimpse,  fuller  or  narrower,  of  the 
Ideas.  That  vision,  when  they  fell  to  the  earth,  they  retained  in  a 
sort  of  latent  memory;  and  so  bring  with  them  to  their  present  life 
the  potentiality  of  true  knowledge.  Under  the  stimulus  of  the  things 
of  this  world,  which  imitate  the  Ideas  or  share  somehow  in  their 
nature,  that  potentiality  is  realised,  or  may  be  realised;  the  ancient 
vision,  called  from  its  latency  into  clear  consciousness,  becomes  what 
we  call  knowledge  or  science,  but  what  truly  is  Eeminiscence.  It  will 

i  Apology,  38A. 
226 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

be  observed  what  this  really  means.  It  means  that,  even  when  Plato 
is  using  the  speech  of  Abstract  Idealism,  the  root  of  Concrete  Idealism 
is  in  him.  For  while  the  form  of  language  used  in  such  a  myth  as 
that  of  the  Phaedrus  sets  the  two  worlds  apart,  its  essential  meaning 
joins  them  together. 

(3)  Under  the  influence    of    the    separation    of    universal    and 
particular,   of    Idea   and   phenomenon,   the  "  stages   of   knowledge " 
come    to    be  represented,    not  so  much  as  stages    in  a  development 
in  which  we  pass  from  the    vague  and    inadequate  to  the    clearer 
and  more  adequate,  from   the  abstract  to  the  concrete,  in  one   word, 
from  the  particulars  in  isolation  to  the  particulars  seen  in  the  light 
of  the  Idea  of  Good  as  elements  or  factors  in  its  realisation;    but 
rather  ,as  different  kinds  of  insight    relating  to    different    orders  of 
objects.    Knowledge  and  opinion  are  different  faculties  and  have  to  do 
with  different  kinds  of  subject-matter.     The  sphere  of   knowledge  is 
being;   but  the  sphere  of  opinion  is  that  mixture  of  being  with  non- 
being  (i.e.,  of  the  Idea  with  empty  space)  which  is  the  present  world. 
The  one  is  absolute  and  infallible,  as  having    grasped  the  supreme 
principle  of  the  real  world  and  seeing  everything  in  its  light.    But  the 
other  is  relative  and  erring,  tossing  about  in  a  region  which  is  half 
way  between  pure  being  and  pure  non-being.1    He  who  has   failed  to 
grasp  the  Idea  of  Good  which  is  the  supreme  principle  of  all  reality 
and  therefore  the  master-light  of  all  vision  of  reality — can  we  allow 
his  "  opinion  "  to  be  a  genuine  stage  on  the  way  to  knowledge  ?    Bather 
we  must  say  of  him  "  that  he  knows  neither  the  essence  of  good,  nor 
any  other  good  thing;    and  that  any   phantom  of  it,  which  he  may 
chance  to  apprehend,  is  the  fruit  of  opinion  and  not  of  science ;   and 
that  he  dreams  and  sleeps  away  his  present  life,  and  never  wakes  on 
this  side  of  that  future    world,  in  which  he  is  doomed  to  sleep  for 
ever."2 

(4)  So  far  as  the  two-world  theory  prevails,  the  rule  of  conduct, 

1  Republic,  476-480.    Cf.  Symposium,  202A,  and  even  Timacus,  51D,  52. 

2  Republic,  534C,  tr.  Davies  and  Vaughan.    Compare  the  treatment  of  "  right  opinion  " 
in  the  Meno  (97-100),  where  the  tone  is  gentler  (though  possibly  with  a  touch  of  irony— e.g., 
in  the  reference  to  that  right  opinion  of  statesmen  which  is  in  politics  what  divination  is 
in  religion— "  for  diviners  and  also  prophets  say  many  things  truly,  but  they  know  not 
what  they  say")  but  the  radical  opposition  itself  is  by  no  means  obscured  or  given  up. 

227 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

"  live  in  accordance  with  the  true  nature  of  the  world,"  comes  to 
mean:  Eise  to  citizenship  in  the  real  world,  and  in  order  to  do  so 
separate  yourself  from  the  life  and  the  ways  of  this  present  world. 
Positively,  that  is  to  say,  the  good  man  is  called  to  a  life  not  of  this 
world.  While,  negatively,  it  is  held  that  the  Good  cannot  be  realised 
under  the  ordinary  forms  of  our  present  experience,  so  far  as  that 
experience  is  one  of  time  and  sense ;  so  that  "  demotic  virtue/'  instead 
of  being  viewed  as  a  genuine  though  inadequate  stage  in  the  realisa 
tion  of  the  Good,  is  regarded  as  a  phantom  of  virtue  calling  for  down 
right  condemnation.  Both  these  sides  of  the  abstract  tendency  come 
frequently  to  expression  in  Plato;  but  the  place  where  they  secure 
their  most  continuous  and  impressive  statement  is — with  singular 
appropriateness — in  the  Phaedo.  The  man  of  philosophic  mind  "  is 
always  pursuing  death  and  dying,"  and  "  has  had  the  desire  of  death 
all  his  life  long."  But  what  is  "  the  nature  of  that  death "  ?  It  is 
that  "  release  of  the  soul  from  the  body  "  which  enables  the  soul  "  to 
exist  in  herself."1  For  the  body  is  a  hinderer  in  the  acquirement  of 
knowledge.  The  senses  which  it  brings  to  the  soul  are  "  inaccurate 
witnesses."2  So  that  the  soul,  if  she  attempt  "  to  consider  anything 
in  company  with  the  body  "  is  "  obviously  deceived  " ;  and  if  she  is  to 
gain  a  revelation  of  true  existence,  must  gain  it  in  that  thought  in 
which  "  the  mind  is  gathered  into  herself,  and  none  of  these  things 
trouble  her, — neither  sights  nor  sounds  nor  pain  nor  any  pleasure,"  in 
which  "  she  takes  leave  of  the  body  and  has  as  little  as  possible  to  do 
with  it,"  in  which  "  she  has  no  bodily  sense  or  desire,  but  is  aspiring 
after  true  being,"  in  which  she  is  free  from  all  the  troubles  and  evils  of 
the  bodily  life,  hunger  and  disease,  "  loves,  and  lusts,  and  fears,  and 
fancies  of  all  kinds,  and  endless  foolery,"  "  wars  and  fightings  and 
factions."3  So  long  as  the  soul  uses  the  body  as  an  instrument  of 
perception  (i.e.,  uses  the  senses),  she  is  "  dragged  by  the  body  into  the 
region  of  the  changeable,  and  wanders  and  is  confused;  the  world 
spins  round  her,  and  she  is  like  a  drunkard,  when  she  touches 
change.  .  .  .  But  when  returning  into  herself  she  reflects,  then 

i  64  ABC.  2  65  A.  s  65,  66. 

228 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

she  passes  into  the  other  world,  the  region  of  purity,  and  eternity,  and 
immortality,  and  unchangeableness,  which  are  her  kindred,  and  with 
them  she  ever  lives,  when  she  is  by  herself  and  is  not  let  or  hindered ; 
then  she  ceases  from  her  erring  ways,  and  being  in  communion  with 
the  unchanging,  is  unchanging/71  It  is  at  this  existence  of  the  soul  in 
herself  alone,  in  which  "  the  soul  in  herself  "  beholds  "  the  realities  of 
things,"  that  philosophy  (in  Plato's  sense  of  the  word)  aims  while 
the  soul  is  still  cumbered  with  the  body.  "  The  lovers  of  knowledge," 
says  Socrates,  "  are  conscious  that  the  soul  was  simply  fastened  and 
glued  to  the  body — until  philosophy  received  her,  she  could  only  view 
real  existence  through  the  bars  of  a  prison,  not  in  and  through 
herself ;  she  was  wallowing  in  the  mire  of  every  sort  of  ignorance,  and 
by  reason  of  lust  had  become  the  principal  accomplice  in  her  own 
captivity.  This  was  her  original  state ;  and  then,  as  I  was  saying,  and 
as  the  lovers  of  knowledge  are  well  aware,  philosophy,  seeing  how 
terrible  was  her  confinement,  of  which  she  was  to  herself  the  cause, 
received  and  gently  comforted  her  and  sought  to  release  her,  pointing 
out  that  the  eye  and  the  ear  and  the  other  senses  are  full  of  deception, 
and  persuading  her  to  retire  from  them,  and  abstain  from  all  but  the 
necessary  use  of  them,  and  be  gathered  up  and  collected  into  herself, 
bidding  her  trust  in  herself  and  her  own  pure  apprehension  of  pure 
existence,  and  to  mistrust  whatever  comes  to  her  through  other 
channels  and  is  subject  to  variation;  for  such  things  are  visible  and 
tangible,  but  what  she  sees  in  her  own  nature  is  intelligible  and 
invisible.  And  the  soul  of  the  true  philosopher  thinks  that  she  ought 
not  to  resist  this  deliverance,  and  therefore  abstains  from  pleasures 
and  desires  and  pains  and  fears,  as  far  as  she  is  able;" — delivering 
herself  thus  from  the  dominion  of  pleasure  and  pain,  because  "  each 
pleasure  and  pain  is  a  sort  of  nail  which  nails  and  rivets  the  soul  to 
the  body,  until  she  becomes  like  the  body,  and  believes  that  to  be  true 
which  the  body  affirms  to  be  true;  and  from  agreeing  with  the  body 
and  having  the  same  delights  she  is  obliged  to  have  the  same  habits 
and  haunts,  and  is  not  likely  ever  to  be  pure  at  her  departure  to  the 
world  below,  but  is  always  infected  by  the  body ;  and  so  she  sinks  into 
another  body,  and  there  germinates  and  grows,  and  has,  therefore,  no 

i  79  CD. 
229 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

part  in  the  communion  of  the  divine  and  pure  and  simple."1  So  that 
philosophy,  while  we  remain  upon  the  earth,  is  a  study  and  practice  of 
death.  But  that  the  long  purification  and  deliverance  may  be  con 
summated,  the  body  must  be  more  than  subdued ;  it  must  die,  so  that 
the  soul  may  take  up  her  dwelling  altogether  "  in  her  own  place  alone." 
And  hence,  when  the  day  of  death  comes,  the  true  lover  of  wisdom  will 
depart  with  joy,  having  "  a  firm  conviction  that  there,  and  there  only, 
he  can  find  wisdom  in  her  purity."2  The  soul  "  which  is  pure  at 
departing,  and  draws  after  her  no  bodily  taint,  having  never  volun 
tarily  during  life  had  connexion  with  the  body,  which  she  is  ever 
avoiding,  herself  gathered  into  herself  ;" — such  a  soul  cannot  "  at  her 
departure  from  the  body  be  scattered  and  blown  away  by  the  winds 
and  be  nowhere  and  nothing,"  but  "herself  invisible,  departs  to  the 
invisible  world — to  the  divine  and  immortal  and  rational:  thither 
arriving,  she  is  secure  of  bliss  and  is  released  from  the  error  and  folly 
of  men,  their  fears  and  wild  passions  and  all  other  human  ills,  and 
for  ever  dwells,  as  they  say  of  the  initiated,  in  company  with  the 
gods."3  While,  on  the  other  hand,  the  virtues  which  do  not  measure 
up  to  this  level — the  "  demotic  "  virtues,  the  virtues  of  men  who  live 
in  the  sphere  of  sense  and  time,  and  are  busy  with  the  matters  of  this 
phantom  world,  and  are  unguided  by  the  vision  of  that  Good  which  is 
the  source  and  form  of  all  virtue: — these  cannot  properly  be  called 
virtues  at  all.  The  courage  of  such  men  is  but  another  form  of  fear. 
They  face  one  evil  because  they  fear  a  greater;  they  are  courageous 
because  they  are  cowards.  Similarly  their  utilitarian  temperance  is 
intemperance;  they  abstain  from  one  pleasure  because  they  desire 
another,  overcoming  pleasure  in  one  form  because  they  themselves  are 
overcome  by  it  in  some  other  form.4  They  do  not  know  that  "  the 
exchange  of  one  fear  or  pleasure  or  pain  for  another  fear  or  pleasure 
or  pain,  and  of  the  greater  for  the  less,  as  if  they  were  coins,  is  not 
the  exchange  of  virtue."5  Wisdom — i.e.,  the  apprehension  of  the  Idea 
of  Good  and  the  viewing  of  things  in  its  light — is  the  "  one  true  coin 
for  which  all  things  ought  to  be  exchanged  " ;  and  the  virtue  which  is 

i  82  E,  83.  2  68  B.  3  80  E,  84  B,  81A. 

*  68  DE.  5  69  A. 

230 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

made  up  of  the  goods  of  the  earth,  severed  from  wisdom  and  exchanged 
with  one  another,  "is  a  shadow  of  virtue  only,  nor  is  there  any 
freedom  or  health  or  truth  in  her."1 

To  sum  up,  then,  what  we  have  so  far  seen,  we  must  say  that  the 
two  tendencies  which  have  been  the  main  currents  in  the  greater 
history  of  philosophy  and  of  religion,  are  both  present  in  Plato :  the 
synthetic,  which  in  philosophy  gives  rise  to  what  we  have  called 
Concrete  Idealism;  and  the  abstract  or  negative,  whose  partial 
triumph  gives  rise  to  Abstract  Idealism,  but  whose  complete  domina 
tion  in  a  profoundly  religious  mind  is  the  source  of  Mysticism.  But 
we  must  also  note  the  relation  in  Plato  of  these  two  tendencies.  The 
tragedy  of  the  world  lay  close  at  his  heart;  and  the  most  impressive 
thing  in  all  his  writing  is  his  prophesying  against  the  world.  But  in 
spite  of  that,  we  must  make  no  mistake  about  the  fact  that  even  in  his 
earlier  and  middle  years  his  deepest  loyalty  is  with  the  synthetic 
tendency.  True,t  its  victory  is  in  this  period  never  complete.  Again 
and  again  Plato  draws  the  line  sharp  and  hard  between  science  and 
opinion,  between  demotic  morality  and  true  virtue,  between  the  soul 
in  the  body  and  the  soul  freed  from  the  body,  between  the  real  world 
and  the  cavern  of  our  sense-experience;  again  and  again  with  sad 
earnestness  he  exhorts  men  to  practise  death  that  they  may  truly  live, 
and  to  fly  from  the  world  to  God.  But  with  all  this,  the  deepest 
impulse  of  his  philosophy  is  toward  an  organic  connexion  of  our 
present  life,  and  of  the  system  of  things  in  which  it  is  lived,  with  the 
ultimate  principle  of  reality.  This,  of  course,  is  a  question  of  the  final 
impression  which  the  whole  body  of  his  writings  in  the  periods  in 
question  makes  upon  the  reader.  But  special  reference  may  be  made 
to  two  subjects  which  already  have  taken  pre-eminent  place  in  his 
thought:  the  state  as  the  greatest  of  human  institutions  for  the 
concrete  realisation  of  the  Good,  by  the  bringing  of  men's  lives  out 
of  confusion,  out  of  self-willed  individualism,  into  an  order  which 
reflects  the  order  of  eternal  reality ;  and  still  more,2  education  as  that 

1  69  B. 

2  Still  more:— because  with  regard  to  the  state,  the  facts  of  the  world  have  driven  him 
partly  to  despair  (Republic,  592) ;  so  that  even  in  its  culmination  as  a  theory  of  the  state, 
his  Idealism  is  touched  by  the  breath  of  the  theologia  negativa — touched  by  its  breath,  not 

231 


PLATO    AND    THE    POUNDING    OP    IDEALISM 

in  which  men,  not  by  suppression  of  the  normal  energies  and  capacities 
of  their  nature,  but  by  the  development  and  discipline  of  these,  are 
led  throughout  the  whole  of  life  in  knowledge  and  in  character  toward 
the  Good. 

But  Plato,  lover  of  truth  for  its  own  sake,  and  master  of  that 
dialectic  method  which  criticises  its  own  conclusion,  and  brings  to 
light  the  further  problems  implicit  in  it,  and  corrects  or  enlarges  it 
until  those  problems  are  adequately  solved,  would  have  been  some 
thing  less  than  himself  if  he  had  left  his  philosophy  in  this  strife  of 
tendencies.  Plato  was  a  man  to  look  his  own  problems  in  the  face ;  and 
therefore  the  passage  of  years  brought  to  his  Idealism  a  steady  growth 
in  thoroughness,  in  self-consistency,  in  mastery  of  its  materials.  He 
felt  that  in  some  genuine  sense  everything  which  you  cannot  decisively 
reject  as  mere  unreality,  mere  void  nothingness,  must  be  organically 
connected  with  the  supreme  principle  of  reality;  indeed,  that  is  the 
cardinal  instinct  of  all  philosophy,  and  its  presence  in  Plato  compelled 
him  to  face  the  problems  that  arose  from  his  tendency  to  separate  the 
world  of  pure  reason  and  perfect  goodness  from  the  world  of  sensible 
and  temporal  experience.  With  these  problems  he  dealt  in  his  later 
period,  which  might  almost  be  described  by  saying  that  in  it  the 
conflict  between  the  two  types  of  Idealism  comes  explicitly  forward, 
and  is  settled,  so  far  as  was  possible  to  him,  in  favour  of  the  Concrete. 


III. 

But  this  brings  us  to  the  third  step  of  our  work.  We  have  to 
consider  that  later  thought  of  Plato  in  which  he  apparently  makes  a 
new  start,  but  really  carries  directly  forward  the  development  of  his 
Idealism.  In  approaching  this  it  is  necessary  to  have  in  mind  the 
exact  situation  in  which  at  the  beginning  of  that  later  thought  he  finds 
himself.  Hence  it  is  advisable  to  note  again,  first,  the  problems  which 
remain  for  him  from  his  earlier  thinking;  secondly,  the  positive 

possessed  by  it,  for  the  cause  of  his  despair  about  the  state  lies  in  the  folly  of  men,  not  in 
any  incommunicability  of  the  Good.  (Compare  as  a  striking,  though  somewhat  poetical, 
instance  of  a  feeling  for  the  organic  connexion  of  civil  society  with  the  "  pattern  laid  up 
in  heaven,"  the  assertion  placed  in  the  mouth  of  Socrates  in  the  Crito  of  the  kinship  of  the 
Athenian  laws  with  those  of  the  world  below.) 

232 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

insight  which  he  carries  forward  with  him  and  upon  which  any 
advance  in  solving  those  problems  must  be  based.  The  problems,  as 
already  we  have  seen,  are  two.  ( 1 )  There  is  a  problem  connected  with 
the  conception  of  the  highest  principle.  If  the  Good  is  to  be  regarded 
as  the  creative  energy  and  organising  principle  of  the  universe,  must 
it  not  be  conceived  as  something  more  than  simply  the  Good ;  namely, 
as  self-conscious  and  self-determining  spirit,  which  constitutes  the 
world  in  view  of  an  end — the  Good — and  shapes  its  structure  and 
process  according  to  definite  types  and  fixed  laws — the  Ideas? 
(2)  There  is  the  problem  raised  for  him  by  that  negative  aspect  of  his 
system  which  we  have  just  been  considering — his  tendency  to  exclude 
from  genuine  reality  the  sense-world  and  the  human  experiences  and 
activities  connected  positively  with  it.  Or,  putting  these  two  problems 
together,  we  may  say,  as  was  noted  above,  that  what  Plato  has  to  face 
is  a  double  incompleteness  in  his  Idealism:  an  incompleteness  at  the 
top — i.e.,  in  its  conception  of  the  highest  principle;  and  a  correspond 
ing  incompleteness  at  the  bottom — the  inability  to  comprehend  the 
sense-world  as  an  organ  and  manifestation  of  the  highest  reality. 
Secondly,  with  regard  to  the  positive  insight  which  Plato  carries 
forward  from  his  earlier  Idealism  to  his  later,  what  we  have  to 
remember  is  this. — If  you  have  been  led  to  draw  a  line  through  the 
universe,  and  to  say  that  what  is  above  this  line  is  truly  real,  while 
what  is  below  it  is  unreal,  or  only  partly  real,  that  mistake  is  not 
necessarily  a  fatal  one.  For  if,  with  regard  to  what  you  do  consider  as 
real,  your  method  is  the  true  one,  the  synthetic  one,  it  is  likely  sooner 
or  later  to  break  the  barrier  which  you  have  erected  around  the  field  of 
its  operation,  and  to  go  forth  to  reclaim  the  banished  parts  of  the 
universe.1  And  this  is  very  nearly  Plato's  case.  For,  however  prone 
he  occasionally  may  be  to  look  upon  the  things  of  the  sense-world  with 
the  eyes  of  a  Mystic,  yet,  as  we  have  already  seen,  when  he  comes  to 
describe  what  to  him  is  the  genuine,  the  undoubtedly  real,  world,  his 
method  is  the  thoroughly  synthetic  method  of  Concrete  Idealism. 

i  In  which  case  your  original  distinction  into  real  and  unreal,  substance  and  shadow, 
is  almost  certain  to  pass  over  into  the  perfectly  sound  and  necessary  distinction  (insisted 
upon  in  our  own  day  by  Mr.  Bradley)  between  the  degrees  of  reality  which  things  have 
accordingly  as  they  are  lower  or  higher  manifestations,  less  or  more  adequate  media,  of 
the  supreme  principle.  Cf.  Caird,  Evolution  of  Theology  in  the  Greek  Philosophers,  vol. 
I.,  pp.  193-197  and  221-259. 

233 


'  PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

The  real  world,  precisely  in  the  name  of  which  he  sometimes  denies 
and  denounces  this  present  world,  is  to  him  no  ineffable  One.  It  is  a 
world  rational  and  rationally  organised.  Eational,  for  it  is  made  up 
of  rational  forms  or  energies  (the  Ideas)  and  rational  distinctions  are 
of  its  very  essence.  And  rationally  organised ;  for  it  has  one  supreme 
principle,  the  Good,  which  is  a  true  universal  of  universals — no  mere 
abstracted  common  element,  but  ar*  eternally  creative  energy,  a  truly 
active  and  organising  principle,  the  source  and  home  and  explanation 
of  all  the  other  Ideas,  of  all  their  differences,  of  all  their  determina 
tions,  and  therefore  of  their  whole  reality  and  their  whole  knowable- 
ness.  Thus  we  may  say  fairly  that  the  central  battle  of  Idealism  is 
already  won  in  the  thinking  of  Plato's  middle  period.  In  fact,  we 
have  seen  reason  for  saying  more  than  that.  As  a  special  evidence  of 
how  that  central  victory  extends  itself  along  the  whole  line,  we  have 
had  to  mark  the  way  in  which  Plato  causes  the  interests  of  the  ideal 
world  to  come  over  and  prevail  concretely  in  this,  in  two  great  realms, 
education  and  the  state:  education  as  advancing  through  orderly 
stages  toward  the  apprehension  of  the  Idea  of  Good;  the  state  as  the 
human  institute  for  its  concrete  realisation. 

We  have  to  turn,  then,  to  the  last  stage  of  Plato's  thought.  In  it, 
as  was  noted  above,  we  seem  to  come  upon  something  new.  The  Ideal 
Theory  seems  to  have  fallen  into  the  background,  and  a  new  inquiry  to 
have  been  made  into  the  constitution  of  the  world,  which  leads  directly 
to  the  conclusion  that  the  world  is  a  work  of  active  intelligence. 
Really,  however,  the  advance  is  continuous,  as  we  shall  see  if  we  follow 
its  own  line  of  movement.  Let  us  consider,  then,  somewhat  more  fully 
just  what  the  problem  is,  which  arises  for  Plato  out  of  the  dualism, 
the  two-world  theory,  toward  which  the  facts  of  life  had  in  earlier 
years  driven  him.  The  problem  raised  by  the  separation  of  the  two 
worlds — whether  the  antithesis  be  left  sharp  and  hard,  or  modified 
into  something  not  far  from  organic  connexion — is  twofold.1  First, 
how  came  this  present  world  into  existence  at  all  ?  Reality  is  with  the 
other  world.  Then  this  world,  if  it  has  any  reality  at  all,  must  have 
its  source  in  that  world.  But  why  does  that  world,  complete  in  its 

i  A  twofold  problem  which,  it  may  be  observed  in  passing,  has  haunted  theology  even 
more  than  philosophy. 

234 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

eternal  perfection,  go  beyond  itself,  to  constitute  another  world,  its 
counterpart  or  its  shadow?  What  is  there  in  its  nature  which  impels 
it  thus  beyond  itself,  and  leads  it  to  communicate  itself,  and  drives  it 
to  the  energies  of  creation?  Secondly,  if  that  world  is  the  source  of 
this,  how  is  it  that  this  world  departs  so  far  from  the  nature  of  that  ? 
how  is  it  that  that  world  has  given  rise  to  something  so  much  unlike 
itself — nay,  so  contradictory  to  itself?  How  from  that  world  of 
reason  and  purity,  of  blessedness  and  perfection,  has  this  scene  of 
imperfection  and  pain,  of  sorrow  and  an  imprisoning  body,  of  folly 
and  madness,  arisen  ?  It  is  with  problems  of  which  the  foregoing  is  a 
statement  in  modern  dress,  that  Plato  deals  in  the  great  group  of 
dialogues — Parmenides,  Sophist,  Statesman,  and  especially  Philebus 
and  Timaeus — in  which  his  philosophy,  laying  aside  at  times  its 
charm  of  expression  and  showing  itself  grey  with  the  labour  of  thought, 
reaches  its  height  of  metaphysical  comprehension. 

First,  then,  how  came  this  present  world  into  being  at  all?  How 
came  the  world  of  Ideas  to  go  outside  of  itself,  to  go  beyond  its  own 
completeness  and  perfection  and  become  the  source  of  another  world? 
Here  it  may  be  advisable  to  pass  at  once  to  Plato's  final  answer,  then 
to  come  back  and  follow  the  argument  by  which  he  leads  up  to  it. 
That  final  answer  is  given  by  an  interpretation  (seen  in  preparation  in 
earlier  writings)  of  the  character  of  that  supreme  principle  of  the  real 
world,  which  formerly  Plato  had  called  the  Idea  of  Good.  It — or 
following  Plato's  example  in  the  Timaeus  let  us  say,  he — "  was  good, 
and  the  good  can  never  have  any  jealousy  of  anything.  And  being  free 
from  jealousy,  he  desired  that  all  things  should  be  as  like  himself  as 
they  could  be."1  That  is  to  say,  it  is  of  the  very  nature  of  the  supreme 
principle  to  communicate  itself,  to  impart  to  others  its  own  being  and 
character  and  blessedness;  so  that  the  nature  itself  of  the  supreme 
principle  is  the  ground  of  the  existence  of  beings,  other  than  the 
supreme  principle,  and  yet  sharing  in  its  nature  and,  therefore,  in  its 
reality. 

So  far  as  this  conclusion  prevails — we  shall  see  presently  that 
Plato  was  not  able  to  carry  it  out  into  all  its  consequences — it  is 
Concrete  Idealism.  The  advance  to  it  which  we  have  now  to  consider, 

1  Timaeus,  29  E. 
235 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OP    IDEALISM 

was  a  long  one.  Its  central  conception,  that  the  supreme  reality  does 
not  stand  apart,  but  is  the  fundamental  energy  of  the  whole  process 
of  the  world,  and  that  it  is  so  because  by  its  very  nature  as  goodness 
it  is  essentially  self -communicative — a  conception  with  which  Plato, 
myths  or  no  myths,  is  thoroughly  in  earnest — is  already  present  in  the 
comparison  of  the  Idea  of  Good  to  the  sun1  in  the  latest-written  section 
of  the  Republic;  and  also  in  the  criticism  of  Anaxagoras  in  the 
Phaedo.2  But  the  dialectical  conquest  of  it  was  no  quick  or  easy 
process.  It  is  worked  out  in  that  group  of  dialogues  which,  logically 
and  perhaps  chronologically,  opens  with  the  Parmenides  and  closes 
with  the  Philebus.  This  great  piece  of  dialectic  has  two  sides ;  a  side 
polemic,  a  side  constructive. 

The  polemic  side — with  an  occasional  pause  to  crush  the  head  of 
materialism  or  sensationalism,  when  these  happen  to  cross  the  path — 
is  directed  in  the  main  against  that  great  argument  of  Parmenides 
which  shuts  reality  up  into  motionlessness  for  ever.  The  spirit  of 
Parmenides  was  very  congenial  to  Plato,  and  wrote  itself  deeply  upon 
certain  aspects  of  his  earlier  Idealism;  "my  father  Parmenides," 
Plato  might  have  said  as  appropriately  as  the  Eleatic  stranger  of  the 
Sophist.3  Yet  the  two  systems  are  at  bottom  completely  irreconcilable. 
If  the  argument  of  Parmenides  could  have  secured  full  right  of  way 
in  Plato's  mind,  it  must  have  shattered  any  form  whatever  of  Idealism ; 
must  (considering  the  religiousness  of  Plato)  have  led  him  at  last  to  a 
complete  Mysticism.  So  that  even  the  earlier  form  of  Plato's  Ideal 
ism  was  built  up  in  the  face  of  Parmenides.  And  if  there  was  to  be 
any  development  of  that  earlier  Idealism,  it  must  make  its  way,  so  to 
speak,  over  the  dead  body  of  the  Parmenidean  argument.  The 
argument  of  Parmenides,  then,  Plato  shatters  in  the  one  way  possible ; 
namely,  by  attacking  it  at  its  source  and  taking  away  that  radical 
disjunction  of  being  and  non-being,  of  is  and  is  not,  upon  which  it  is 
based.  This  is  done  by  showing  that  non-being  exists  and  is  a  kind 
of  being;  the  meaning  of  which,  in  modern  speech,  is,  that  reality  is 
not  an  indivisible  one,  but  that  there  are  differences  and  distinctions 

i  Republic,  506  E-509.  2  97.99,  especially  99.  3  241  E. 

236 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

within  it;  that  reality,  so  far  from  being  an  undifferentiated  and 
ineffable  unity,  is  a  rational  system.1 

This  having  been  done,  the  way  is  open  for  the  constructive 
advance.  By  a  very  keen  argument  (which,  it  is  worthy  of  note, 
proceeds  explicitly  from  the  question  of  the  possibility  of  knowledge) 
it  is  shown  that  in  true  being  there  is  motion — "  motion  and  life  and 
soul  and  mind."  True  being  is  not  "  devoid  of  life  and  mind."  It 
does  not  "  exist  in  awful  meaninglessness,  an  everlasting  fixture."  And 
having  mind  and  life,  it  must  "  have  a  soul  which  contains  them." 
And,  furthermore,  having  life  and  mind  and  soul,  it  cannot  "  remain 
absolutely  unmoved."2  In  the  Pliilebus,  the  view  thus  prepared  for 
comes  to  pointed  expression.  Mind  is  "  king  of  heaven  and  earth." 
It  "  orders  all  things  " ;  for  "  all  this  which  they  call  the  universe  "  is 
not  "  left  to  the  guidance  of  unreason  and  chance  medley,"  but  is  "  as 
our  fathers  have  declared,  ordered  and  governed  by  a  marvellous 
intelligence  and  wisdom."3 

Thus,  then,  the  real  world  comes  explicitly  to  be  conceived  as  a 
world  of  rational  activity,  and  its  highest  principle  as  at  once  the 
supreme  intelligence  and  supreme  energy  of  the  universe,  acting  in 
"  creation  "  and  in  "  providence  "4  according  to  its  nature  as  reason 
and  goodness.  And  with  this  the  view  of  the  Timaeus,  stated  above — 
the  view  that  the  perfect  God,  being  good,  is  led  by  His  nature  to 
communicate  Himself  and  so  becomes  the  author  and  father  of  the 
universe — is  made  possible,  not  merely  as  a  prophetic  insight,  but  as 
the  culmination  of  a  reasoned  Idealism. 

So  far,  we  have  been  following  Plato's  own  line  of  advance.  But 
at  this  point  let  us  stop  to  consider  how  far  the  problems  left  over 
from  the  earlier  Idealism  have  been  met  in  the  argument  just  outlined. 
Those  problems,  it  will  be  remembered,  were  two :  one,  so  to  speak,  at 
the  top,  the  other  at  the  bottom,  of  the  Platonic  Idealism;  one  con 
nected  with  the  conception  of  the  highest  principle,  the  other  with  the 
interpretation  of  the  sense-world.  And  the  latter  breaks  again  into 
two :  ( 1 )  Upon  the  two-world  theory,  how  do  you  account  for  this 

i  Sophist,  241  E— 260.    It  is  interesting  to  compare  Hegel's  Logic. 
i  Sophist,  246-249.  3  Philebus,  28.  4  Timaeus,  30. 

237 


PLATO  AND  THE  FOUNDING  OF  IDEALISM 

present  world  at  all — why,  when  the  real  world  is  eternally  perfect  and 
complete,  did  it  go  out  of  itself  to  give  rise  to  another  world? 
(2)  When  the  real  world  became  the  source  of  this,  why  did  it  appar 
ently  contradict  its  own  nature,  giving  rise  to  a  world  so  different  from 
iself ,  so  imperfect  and  so  evil  ?  It  will  be  seen  that  the  argument  which 
we  have  just  been  following,  brings  forward — though  it  does  not  with 
any  fulness  articulate — the  conceptions  necessary  for  solving  the  first  of 
these  problems  and  the  first  part  of  the  second.  And  it  furnishes  a 
basis  for  dealing  with  the  remaining  part  of  the  second.  For  such  a 
view  makes  it  possible  to  regard  this  present  world  as  in  organic  con 
nexion  with  the  highest  principle  of  reality.  When  that  principle  is 
viewed  as  active  and  self-determining  reason,  and  as  a  goodness  which 
cannot  remain  in  itself,  but  is  led  by  its  very  nature  to  go  out  of  itself 
and  communicate  itself,  it  is  scarcely  possible  to  regard  this  present 
world,  and  all  worlds, — "  all  time  and  all  existence  " — as  anything 
other  than  as  the  field  of  its  activity,  the  process  in  which  it  fulfils  its 
own  nature  by  communicating  itself  and  so  realising  the  Good.  And 
such  a  view,  if  he  could  clearly  have  entered  into  it,  would  have 
enabled  Plato  to  look  with  eyes  of  faith  upon  those  aspects  of  the 
present  world  which  so  grieved  him.  Its  imperfection,  its  struggle 
and  unrest,  its  tragedies  of  unrewarded  toil,  of  baffled  devotion,  of 
defeated  righteousness,  would  have  been  accepted  by  him  as  elements 
in  a  process  in  which  a  wisdom,  too  vast  for  us  to  understand  its 
separate  steps,  is  fulfilling  itself. 

Does  Plato,  then,  take  this  last  step,  which  would  have  made  his 
Idealism  as  thoroughly  concrete  as  is  possible  to  human  insight  ?  The 
anwer  falls  into  two  parts. 

First,  he  took  up  positions  which  look  toward  it,  which,  one  might 
almost  say,  contain  it  implicitly.  In  the  Philebus,  for  instance,  he 
puts  the  capstone  upon  the  argument  which  was  outlined  a  moment 
ago  by  applying  it  directly  to  man's  life.  The  characters  of  the 
divinely  organised  universe — Beauty,  Symmetry,  Truth1 — are  to  be 
adopted  by  man  as  the  characters  to  be  realised  in  his  own  nature  and 
life.  But  the  most  striking  instance  of  all  is  furnished  by  a  work  of 
Plato's  which  is  described  sometimes  as  a  falling  from  faith,  as  a 

i  Philebus,  65  A. 

238 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

forsaking  of  the  height  for  the  lowland,  or  even  as  an  example  of  the 
hollowness  of  philosophy  which  fails  its  disciples  at  the  last;  but 
which  in  truth  is  one  of  the  most  nobly  pathetic  chapters  in  the 
spiritual  history  of  man.  For  that  is  what  we  must  say  of  the  Laws 
when  we  consider  the  position  it  holds  in  Plato's  life.  Much  earlier, 
as  was  pointed  out  above,  the  essential  concreteness  in  the  temper  of 
his  Idealism  manifested  itself  in  his  devotion  to  the  state.  It  had  been 
the  greatest  work  of  his  middle  life  to  set  before  his  disciples  a  picture 
of  the  state  as  it  should  be.  Then,  in  later  years,  endeavouring  to  make 
his  presentation  of  the  true  polity  more  concrete,  he  entered  upon  that 
magnificently  conceived  design  which  would  have  given  an  almost  epic 
completeness  to  the  Republic,  but  of  which  the  Timaeus  is  the  only 
finished  part.  The  ideal  state  he  had  described.  Now  he  would  show 
it  taking  its  place  and  discharging  its  function  in  the  world,  holding 
its  own  in  struggle,  and  showing  "  by  the  greatness  of  its  actions  and 
the  magnanimity  of  its  words  in  dealing  with  other  cities  a  result 
worthy  of  its  training  and  education/'1  To  this  end,  Timaeus  was  to 
begin  with  the  generation  of  the  world  and  carry  its  story  down  to  the 
creation  of  man ;  and  then  Critias  was  to  receive  the  men  thus  created, 
and  show  the  place  and  life  and  work  of  the  ideal  state  by  describing 
how  an  Athens,  which  once  was,  maintained  the  freedom  of  the  whole 
of  Europe  and  Asia,  when  a  mighty  power  from  the  Atlantic  made  an 
expedition  against  them.2  But  even  this  was  not  enough.  The  desire 
to  bring  the  ideal  into  some  more  feasible  connexion  with  the  life  and 
ordinary  nature  of  man,  led  to  another  step;  and  that  step  was  the 
Laws.  At  the  end  of  his  life,  when  we  should  have  expected  his  con 
nexion  with  the  world  to  be  growing  fainter,  his  aloofness  from  it  to 
be  increasing — precisely  then  it  was  that  Plato,  seeking  at  least  some 
measure  of  the  effective  operation  of  the  heavenly  ideal  in  the  affairs 
of  the  earth,  bent  his  sublime  head,  and  turned  to  the  daily  life  and 
unaspiring  minds  of  men,  and  outlined — in  a  collection  of  sketches 
and  fragments  edited  by  some  later  hand — a  "  second-best "  constitu 
tion,  more  applicable,  as  he  thought,  to  the  life  of  this  present  world 
than  that  polity  which  in  earlier  days  he  had  sketched  in  strict 

i  Timaeus,  19  C.  2  Timaeus,  27A,  24  E. 

239 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

following  of  the  pattern  laid  up  in  heaven.  The  endeavour  of  the 
Laws  is  no  apostasy  from  Idealism;  it  represents  no  loss  of  belief  in 
the  heavenly  pattern.  But  it  is  a  recognition  that  there  is  a  difference 
between  heaven  and  earth,  between  the  eternal  ideal  and  the  present 
state  of  human  affairs ;  that,  therefore,  it  is  vain  to  expect  in  one  step 
and  by  one  single  stroke  to  realise  the  order  of  heaven  in  the  life  of  the 
earth;  for  the  ideal  realises  itself  through  many  intermediate  stages, 
and  the  only  way  to  fee  heavenly  glory  is  by  making  the  best  of  this 
present  twilight.  Indeed,  Plato  almost  reverses  what  we  commonly 
take  to  be  the  normal  relation  of  the  abstract  and  the  concrete  theology 
in  a  man's  life.  We  usually  expect  that  a  man  will  begin  life  with 
delight  in  this  world,  with  thoughtless  participation  in  its  interests 
and  enjoyments;  and  then,  when  he  grows  old  and  the  graver  and 
longer  interests  of  the  soul  enforce  their  claim,  that  he  will  look  away 
from  this  world  toward  heaven.  But  Plato  belongs  to  another  order 
of  men.  These,  by  native  purity  and  loftiness  of  mind,  aided,  it  may 
be,  by  some  hopeless  sorrow,  are  brought  early  in  life  to  feel  that 
"  whatsoever  is  not  God,  is  nothing,  and  ought  to  be  accounted  as 
nothing."1  And  from  this  they  draw  the  great  practical  lessons, 
de  neglectu  omnis  creaturae,  ut  Creator  possit  inveniri,  and  de  se 
tenendo  tamquam  exule  et  peregrino  super  terrain.2  But  as  life  goes 
on,  and  reflexion  deepens,  and  religion  joins  hands  with  reason,  and 
the  world's  great  need  forces  itself  upon  the  mature  soul,  more  and 
more  they  turn,  with  a  certain  grave  and  wistful  devotion,  to  take 
their  places  in  the  world  and  to  give  their  hearts  to  its  labours,  its 
interests,  its  causes.  And  Plato,  though  there  was  no  statesman's  post 
for  him  at  Syracuse  or  Athens,  found  at  last  his  place.  It  has  already 
been  noted  how  his  defeated  passion  for  the  state  answers  to  the 
defeated  political  hope  of  Wordsworth.  The  parallelism  holds  to  the 
end.  Each  found,  for  the  problem  of  his  practical  life  and  personal 
activity,  the  same  solution ;  of  each,  one  can  say  in  Windelband's  fine 
expression,3  seine  That  ist  seine  Lelire.  For  each,  the  defeated  passion 
in  him,  and  the  mighty  thoughts  that  had  grown  in  the  soil  of  that 

i  De  Imitations  Christi,  III.  31.  2. 

2  Ibid.  III.  31,  and  I.  17. 1. 

3  Platon,  S.  29. 

240 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

defeat,  found  expression  by  voice  and  pen;  and,  iinding  expression, 
entered  upon  a  field  of  influence  greater  than  ever  was  given  to 
statesman  entrusted  with  the  framing  of  constitutions,  or  the 
administering  of  affairs,  in  Sicily  or  Athens  or  Paris ;  going  forth  to 
be  a  guide  and  an  inspiration,  while  the  world  of  men  continues,  to 
the  highest  hearts  in  every  land. 

There  are,  then,  in  Plato's  later  thought — especially  in  his 
practical  interest,  his  interest  in  education  and  the  state — positions 
which  imply  the  organic  connexion  of  this  present  world,  marred 
though  it  is  by  evil  and  unrest,  with  the  final  principle  of  reality. 
But,  as  was  indicated  above,  this  is  only  part  of  the  answer  to  the 
question  now  before  us.  The  other  part  is,  that  with  regard  to  the 
world  of  sensible  experience,  this  implicit  view  is  never  brought  to 
clear  articulation;  on  the  contrary,  in  Plato's  express  doctrine  the 
opposite  view  prevails  to  the  end. 

In  the  last  analysis,  the  cause  of  this  failure  clearly  and  unwaver 
ingly  to  view  the  world  of  sensible  experience  as  a  manifestation  of  the 
supreme  principle  of  reality  lies  in  the  fact  that  Plato's  latest 
conception  of  that  supreme  principle  never  quite  comes  to  its 
rights.  If  he  had  been  able  clearly  to  articulate  his  conception  of 
that  principle  as  active  intelligence  and  self-imparting  goodness 
— in  one  word,  as  self-determining  and  self-communicating  spirit — he 
would  have  been  compelled  to  view  the  sense-world,  and  our  experience 
in  it,  as  a  stage  of  the  process  in  which  that  principle  is  fulfilling  its 
nature  and  realising  its  purpose.  But  only  in  many  ages,  only  in 
many  leaders  of  the  thought  of  the  ages,  could  so  great  a  work  be 
done.  To  no  one  man  was  so  great  an  intellectual  achievement 
possible.  Plato,  we  may  say,  hit  the  core  of  the  solution ;  but  it  was 
scarcely  given  to  him  to  go  back  over  all  his  system,  and  in  the  light 
of  that  central  truth  to  work  it  into  a  thoroughly  articulated  view  of 
the  world. 

For  one  thing,  ancient  thought  had  not  clearly  apprehended  the 
nature  of  self-consciousness  or  spirit  as  it  is  in  man  himself.  When 
you  have  seen  that  the  self-consciousness,  which  is  man,  in  a  sense 
constitutes  its  own  objects  and  so  "  makes  nature  " ;  and  that  in  doing 
this  it  exercises  a  synthetic  power — is  an  active  principle  of  unity  in 

17  241 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

diversity,  linking  many  facts  into  one  experience  and  thus  constituting 
both  the  facts  which  make  up  the  experience  and  the  experience  which 
is  made  up  of  the  facts : — then  you  can  advance  with  secure  footing  to 
the  view  that  the  principle  of  union  implied  in  the  existence  of  the 
universe  is  a  self-conscious  and  self-determining  spirit  which  consti 
tutes  and  links  into  one  system  the  apparently  conflicting  facts  of  the 
world,  and  through  many  stages  wherein  men  suffer,  and  are  blessed, 
and  at  last  become  truly  themselves,  realises  its  purpose.  But  an 
insight  into  the  synthetic  or  creative  energy  of  self-consciousness  as 
it  is  in  man  never  became  the  explicit  point  of  departure  for  Hellenic 
thought.1  Hence,  while  it  was  possible  for  Plato  to  come  to  the  belief 
that  mind  is  "  king  of  heaven  and  earth  "  and  "  orders  all  things,"  it 
was  scarcely  possible  for  him  to  articulate  that  belief  into  a  thoroughly 
organic  view  of  the  world. 

We  shall  best  see  this,  however,  by  turning  to  Plato's  own  treat 
ment  of  the  problem  now  before  us.  Granted — so  that  problem  stands 
—that  the  supreme  principle  of  the  real  world,  being  good,  must  go 
beyond  itself  to  communicate  its  nature  and  impart  its  blessedness, 
why  must  the  created  world  be  one  of  imperfection?  Why  is  it  not 
like  its  source  in  perfection  and  blessedness?  Has  not  the  supreme 
principle,  in  going  out  into  such  a  world,  contradicted  rather  than 
obeyed  its  own  nature? 

The  part  of  Plato's  theory  which  corresponds  to  this  question  may 
be  put  in  this  way. — When  the  supreme  principle  goes  out  of  itself 
upon  that  creative  activity,  into  what  region  does  it  go  forth  ?  Mani 
festly  into  the  region  of  non-being.  So  that  the  created  world  is  a 
mixture  of  being  and  non-being.  That  is  to  say,  it  is  a  world  of 
becoming,  and  therefore  of  imperfection,  and  of  all  the  evils  of 
imperfection. 

But  such  an  answer  has  two  possible  meanings.  Upon  the  first 
meaning,  the  total  explanation  of  this  going  out  into  the  region  of 
non-being  and  creating  there  a  world  which  is  a  mixture  of  being  and 
non-being  and  is,  therefore,  subject  to  imperfection  and  evil,  lies  in 
the  divine  nature  itself  which  thus  goes  forth.  In  other  words,  it  is 
affirmed  that  the  supreme  principle  must  begin  its  creative  work  with 

i  Windelband,  op.  cit.  S.  74. 
242 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

something  less  than  perfection — something  less  than  completely 
realised  "  Being  " — in  order  to  achieve  its  purpose  at  all.  If  it  is  to 
fulfil  its  purpose,  that  communication  of  itself  to  other  beings  to 
which  it  is  impelled  by  its  nature,  must  not  be  a  creation  of  perfection 
by  perfection.  For  in  that  case  the  perfection  of  the  created  beings 
would  be,  after  all,  a  sort  of  sham  battle;  would  be  a  sort  of  gaining 
the  goal  without  running.  To  lay  aside  metaphor,  it  would  be  only  an 
apparent  perfection,  being  radically  flawed  by  the  fact  that  those  who 
have  it,  were  absolutely  passive  in  the  acquiring  of  it.  If  it  is  really 
to  be  their  perfection,  and  not  just  a  divine  perfection  laid  upon  them 
from  the  outside,  they  must  themselves  conquer  it;  they  must  them 
selves  be  active,  must  themselves  labour  and  suffer,  in  the  process  of 
its  attainment.  They  must,  therefore,  begin  not  at  the  top  of  the 
scale,  but  somewhere  lower.  In  Plato's  language  they  must  begin  out 
in  the  region  of  non-being.  Beginning  there,  they  must  work  their 
way  toward  true  and  pure  being,  by  a  process  in  which  their  own 
labour  and  struggle  is  answered  by  ever  increasing  impartations  to 
them  of  the  divine  nature. 

This,  then,  is  one  possible  meaning  of  the  view  that  creation  is  a 
process  in  which  being  goes  out  into  the  region  of  non-being;    and 
that  the  world  which  arises  is  consequently  a  mixture  of  being  and 
non-being,  an  order,  that  is .  to  say,  of  becoming  and  imperfection. 
And  such  a  view  is  Concrete  Idealism.    For  it  sees  this  world  of  time 
in  organic  connexion  with  the  realities  of  eternity.    It  sees  this  present  / 
order  .of  things,  and  our  human  struggle  upward  through  its  imper-  I 
fection  and  evil,  as  a  process  in  which,  by  no  sham  battle,  but  by  most 
real  achievement,  the  divine  nature  fulfils  itself  by  imparting  itself  to, 
other  beings. 

But  upon  the  other  meaning,  the  explanation  of  the  fact  that  the 
created  world  is  blended  of  being  and  non-being  is  made  to  lie,  not  in 
the  essential  nature  and  conditions  of  the  divine  activity  in  creation, 
but  in  the  nature  of  the  region  of  non-being  into  which  that  activity 
goes  forth.  Non-being,  that  is  to  say,  really  is  viewed  as  a  second 
eternal  principle  of  things.  It  is  regarded  as  having  a  nature  of  its 
own,  power  of  its  own;  as  being  able,  by  "its  stubbornness,  its  recalci-  I 
trancy,  its  unsuitability  to  the  divine  forms  which  are  to  be  impressed 

243 


.PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

upon  it,  to  thwart  or  impede  the  creative  energies  of  the  divine  nature, 
and  so  to  diminish  the  perfection  of  the  created  world.  And  upon  the 
whole  it  is  to  this  view  that  Plato  is  driven.  His  general  description 
of  non-being — that  it  is  a  mere  potentiality  of  taking  on  form,  an 
incomprehensible  something  which  receives  all  things;1  his  particular 
description  of  it  is  empty  space2: — these  pass  over  into  statements 
which  imply  that  non-being  is,  somehow,  more  than  a  mere  empty  field 
in  which  being  can  work,  more,  that  is  to  say,  than  the  mere  possi 
bility  of  creation.  It  has  a  power  of  positive  resistance  in  it;  this  is 
explicitly  called  Necessity,3  and  is  viewed  as  a  co-eternal  principle  able 
to  limit  and  hinder  the  purely  rational  creative  energy,  so  that  the 
resultant  world  is  not  purely  rational,  but  is  a  mixture  of  sense  and 


reason.4 

So  that  to  the  end  there  is  a  measure  of  dualism  in  Plato.  Indeed, 
for  him  there  is  no  escape  from  it.  For,  on  the  one  hand,  he  was 
acutely  conscious  of  the  imperfection  of  the  world.  And,  on  the  other 
hand,  in  his  day  it  was  not  possible  for  human  thought  to  conceive  the 
intelligent  and  self-communicating  goodness,  which  is  the  supreme 
principle  of  reality,  as  fulfilling  its  purpose  of  self-communication  by  a 
process  which  begins  with  something  lower  than  its  own  eternal 
perfection;  by  a  process,  that  is  to  say,  which,  to  the  created  beings 
standing  in  it,  is  one  of  evolution  and  of  the  struggle  and  suffering 
that  evolution  involves. 


IV. 

Plato's  philosophy,  then,  was  one  that  laboured  toward  concrete- 
ness  ;  laboured  toward  a  conception  of  the  highest  reality  as  a  mind 
perfect  in  reason  and  goodness,  self-communicating,  and  therefore  the 
author  and  father  of  a  universe.  But  to  the  end  that  effort  is  in  part 
defeated.  Plato's  acute  sense  of  the  evil  in  the  present  world  makes 
him  feel  that  it  is  deeply  sundered  from  genuine  reality;  while,  on 
the  other  hand,  he  has  not  entered  sufficiently  into  possession  of  his 

i  Timaeus,  51  A.  2  Timaeus,  52.  3  Tiinaeus,  48  A,  56  C. 

*  Timaeus,  44  (of.  Phaedo,  66). 

244 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

highest  conception  to  be  enabled — or  rather,  to  be  compelled — to  view 
the  supreme  mind  as  a  synthetic  principle  realising  itself  through  the 
total  process  of  the  world. 

So  that  a  measure  of  the  negative  theology  is  in  him  to  the  end. 
And  it  makes  him  grave  and  austere.  We  have  already  seen  how  in 
the  very  years  when  his  hold  upon  life  and  his  delight  in  its  greater 
energies  must  have  been  at  the  height,  a  certain  stern  and  sad  and 
uncompromising  aloofness  marked  even  his  devotion  to  the  state. 
Scarcely  can  the  true  statesman  bear  rule  in  the  city  of  his  birth.  The 
"  city  which  is  his  own  "  has  its  pattern  laid  up  in  heaven.  It  he  will 
seek  to  behold,  and  in  accordance  with  it  will  organise  his  life.  But 
"  with  any  other  city  he  will  have  nothing  to  do."1  And  something  of 
this  temper  remained  in  him  throughout  life.  Hardly  can  he  reconcile 
himself  to  the  world.  To  the  last  it  stands  at  the  bar  of  his  thought 
as  a  product  of  perfect  reason,  but  perfect  reason  working  in  an  alien 
realm  and  upon  alien  material  and  prevented  thereby  from  fulfilling 
itself;  while  the  religious  spirit  in  him  feels  instinctively  that  the 
reality  with  which  it  longs  to  be  at  one  is  something  far  other  than  this 
world,  something  far  removed  from  the  whole  order  of  things,  the 
whole  system  of  life,  which  has  its  being  in  space  and  time.  And  so 
to  the  end  he  continues  to  speak  in  that  characteristic  note  and  tone 
which  in  all  ages  has  drawn  to  him  high  and  pure  hearts  to  whom  the 
penetrating  insights  of  his  science  were  a  closed  book — the  note  and 
tone  of  the  man  who,  having  lifted  up  his  mind  to  the  things  that  are 
eternal,  prophesies  against  the  world,  and  exhorts  men  to  fly  from  the 
world  to  God. 

Thus  the  Greek  spirit  was  transformed  in  Plato.  Its  mastery  over 
the  resources  of  the  present  life,  its  habitual  delight  in  the  activities 
of  the  day  that  now  is,  its  quick  susceptibility  to  every  interesting 
thing  and  every  beautiful  form  that  the  world  affords,  its  proneness 
to  lose  itself  in  these  and  make  the  most  of  them  before  the  evil  days 
come  in  which  the  pale  shade  has  no  more  delight  in  life : — all  this  was 
in  Plato,  but  in  him  as  something  that  stands  rebuked.  Always  he 
had  disliked  the  volatility  and  fickleness  of  the  Athenians  of  his  day ; 
always  his  sympathy  had  been  with  the  grave  strength  of  the  men  of 

i  Republic,  592. 

245 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

Marathon  or  the  austere  discipline  of  Sparta.  And  upon  all  this  there 
had  supervened  an  infinitely  prof ounder  spiritual  power,  against  which 
his  science  made  gradual  headway,  but  which  it  could  never  wholly 
overcome — the  tendency  of  a  pure  and  high  mind,  and  of  a  heart 
religious  with  the  religion  of  eternity,  toward  the  absolute  condemna 
tion  of  the  things  of  the  world  in  the  light  of  a  vision  of  the  heavenly 
perfection. 

When  the  genius  of  Greece  still  was  young,  and  interpreted  the 
life  of  nature  in  accordance  with  the  life  of  its  own  soul,  it  shaped  out 
in  legend  an  unintentional  prophecy  of  this  transformation  which  it 
was  itself  to  undergo  when  its  doom  was  descending  upon  it,  and  in 
the  soul  of  its  greatest  son  it  turned  itself  toward  the  things  of 
eternity.  The  daughter  of  the  earth-goddess  led  the  life  of  a  happy 
child,  playing  among  the  flowers  in  the  meadows  of  Enna,  lost  in 
momentary  pleasures,  absorbed  in  momentary  griefs.  Very  direct  and 
simple  was  the  unity  of  her  mind  with  the  beauty  that  surrounded  her, 
and  with  her  home  the  kindly  earth ;  and  her  heart  was  very  close  to 
her  mother's  heart — for  there  was  no  barrier  of  knowledge  or  of  vision 
or  of  experience  that  could  come  between.  But  when  Hades  suddenly 
had  taken  her  to  him,  and  set  her  at  his  side  on  the  inexorable  throne 
from  which  the  issues  of  all  things  mortal  are  seen;  and  when 
Demeter,  making  desolate  the  earth,  had  compelled  the  restitution  of 
her  child  for  the  happier  seasons  of  the  year: — she  who  returned  to 
Demeter's  arms  was  not  she  who  had  gone.  Persephone  it  was;  but 
no  longer  the  happy  child  of  the  Sicilian  meadows.  A  stately  queen 
she  came,  in  her  eyes  the  unfathomable  wisdom  of  the  kingdom  of  the 
dead,  in  her  bearing  the  majesty  of  the  dark  king  her  mate,  at  her 
heart  a  grave  astonishment  as  she  looked  upon  the  hapless  creatures, 
her  mother's  friends,  the  men  who  till  the  earth,  and  struggle  for 
things  that  pass  away,  and  mourn  as  the  objects  of  their  foolish  quests 
perish  in  their  hands.  Never  while  the  system  of  the  universe  endured 
could  Demeter  have  her  child  again.  Henceforward  she  must  walk 
through  all  her  genial  summers,  companioning,  not  with  a  happy 
child,  but  with  the  majestic  woman  whose  eyes,  "  imperial,  disimpas- 
sioned,"  had  gazed  upon  uttermost  mysteries  and  ultimate  doom. 
And  yet  it  may  be  that  Demeter,  having  thus  undergone  her  fate,  came 

246 


PLATO    AND    THE    FOUNDING    OF    IDEALISM 

at  last  to  find  it  good ;  for  it  may  be  that  the  nature  of  the  Immortal 
Gods,  unchangeable  at  her  heart,  caused  her  at  last  to  rejoice  with  a 
joy  that  had  never  been  in  her  life  before,  when  she  found  at  her  side 
no  longer  the  child  that  played  in  Enna  and  by  night  lay  close  to  her 
mother's  heart,  but  a  companion  god,  thinking  godlike  thoughts, 
achieving  godlike  things,  queen  of  the  world  of  the  dead. 

The  genius  of  Greece  might  in  this  almost  have  been  speaking  of 
itself.  The  philosophy  of  Plato  is  the  Persephone's  journey  of  the 
Greek  spirit.  In  him  it  looked  upon  ultimate  things,  and  so  was  led 
to  regard  with  other  eyes  the  life  of  the  earth.  And  undoubtedly  the 
"  hidden  wisdom  of  the  world  "  was  in  this.  For  while  it  is  true  that 
the  beginnings  of  human  life,  and  its  divinely  appointed  end,  are  in 
organic  connexion,  it  is  also  true  that  the  end  is  far  from  the  begin 
ning;  a  great  journey,  a  mighty  discipline,  lie  between.  Earth  and 
heaven  are  parts  of  one  universe;  but  earth  is  very  different  from 
heaven,  and  the  ascent  is  steep  and  long.  The  nature  of  the  world,  and 
the  meaning  of  life,  can  be  known  only  in  the  light  of  the  divinely 
intended  synthesis  toward  which  the  whole  creation  moves;  but  the 
very  vision  of  that  synthesis  is  false  vision  unless  it  makes  clear  how 
far  apart  the  antithetic  members  of  the  system  now  stand,  and  how 
vast  must  be  the  process  that  reconciles  them  in  the  life  of  the  ultimate 
city  of  God.  Hence  the  men  of  the  negative  theology,  though  they 
have  overstated  their  truth  and  made  the  difference  between  eternal 
reality  and  our  present  life  absolute  and  hopeless,  yet  by  their  very 
insistence  upon  the  difference  itself,  have  done  profound  service  to 
humanity.  We  all  need  their  lesson;  and  need  it  the  more  that  our 
age  is  altogether  disinclined  to  learn  it.  A  few  can  learn  it  in  the 
school  of  the  Mystics.  But  most  of  us,  touched,  if  not  controlled,  by 
the  scientific  mind  of  our  day,  and  devoted  practically  to  mastering  the 
things  of  the  world,  can  learn  it  only  as  it  takes  on  humane  forms  and 
goes  hand  in  hand  with  the  synthetic  spirit  of  science.  And  precisely 
thus  it  is  that  it  appears  in  the  urbane  but  solemn  teaching  of  the 
great  son  of  Ariston. 


247 


THE   COMPLETING   OF   IDEALISM 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM. 

I. 

IN  considering  the  Idealism  of  Plato,  we  found  that  the  positive 
tendency  was  not  able  in  him  fully  to  reach  its  goal.  Something  of 
the  negative  view  remains  with  him  to  the  end.  In  the  world,  he 
continues  to  the  last  to  feel,  there  is  a  necessity  which  is  no  manifesta 
tion  of  the  divine  nature,  no  aspect  of  the  divine  activity,  but  an  alien 
force  able  to  prevent  the  divine  nature,  in  its  creation,  from  mani 
festing  and  realising  itself  as  it  does  when  it  works  in  its  own  realm 
where  time  and  space  are  not.  So  that  even  in  his  latest  and  ripest 
thought  he  still  tends  to  condemn  the  present  world,  not  only  ethically, 
as  an  order  of  imperfection,  but  metaphysically,  as  not  being  truly  real. 

The  ultimate  cause  of  this  incompleteness  of  the  Platonic  Idealism 
we  must  call  again  to  mind.  We  saw1  that  the  highest  conception  of 
Idealism  is  the  conception  of  self-determining  and  self-communicating 
spirit  as  the  principle  of  union,  the  constitutive  and  governing  power, 
of  the  universe.  It  is  only  through  this  conception  that  human 
thought  can  comprehend  the  possibility  of  the  organic  connexion  and 
unity  of  all  existences  under  one  supreme  principle  in  one  completely 
rational  world ;  only  through  it,  that  is  to  say,  that  Idealism  becomes 
truly  concrete.  And  we  also  saw  that  the  place  where  man  gains  that 
conception  of  spirit  is  his  own  soul.  When  you  have  apprehended  the 
self-consciousness  which  is  man,  as  an  active  principle  of  synthesis; 
and  have  advanced  to  the  thought  of  a  self-conscious  spirit,  not 
discursive  and  defective  as  in  man,  but  eternal  and  perfect,  as  the 
universal  principle  of  synthesis;  and  have  come  thus  to  regard  the 
order  of  the  universe  as  an  order  constituted  by  that  eternally  active 
spirit,  and  the  process  of  the  universe  as  a  teleological  process  in  which 
that  spirit  fulfils  its  nature  and  realises  its  purpose  by  continually 

i  Supra,  pp.  64-79. 
251 


THE    COMPLETING    OP    IDEALISM 

increasing  impartations  of  itself : — then  at  last  your  Idealism  is  in  its 
ground-lines  self-consistent  and  concrete.  For  then,  without  contra 
dicting  your  own  view  of  the  nature  of  ultimate  reality,  you  can  regard 
this  world,  and  the  conditions  of  our  life  in  it,  as  in  organic  connexion 
with  that  ultimate  reality.  That  eternal  spirit,  in  going  forth  into  a 
world  of  space  and  time,  is  not  going  out  into  an  alien  realm,  nor 
working  upon  alien  material,  but  is  fulfilling  its  own  nature ;  is  acting 
altogether  from  itself,  has  the  sources  of  its  action  altogether  within 
itself.  While  from  our  side,  this  imperfect  knowledge  of  ours  is  a 
stage  on  the  way  to  perfect  knowledge,  this  half-intelligent  demotic 
morality  a  stage  on  the  way  to  a  morality  that  clearly  apprehends  the 
divine  idea  which  it  is  fulfilling.  The  whole  process  of  the  world,  in 
one  word — with  that  imperfect  knowledge  of  ours,  and  that  demotic 
morality,  as  factors  in  it — is  a  process  in  which,  stage  after  stage, 
through  the  struggle  necessary  to  genuine  achievement,  the  divine 
purpose  is  fulfilling  itself,  the  Good  being  realised. 

Plato's  whole  interpretation  of  the  world  as  rational  is  a  call  for 
such  a  conception.  In  his  treatment  of  the  Idea  of  Good  as  the 
organising  principle  of  reality,  as  the  principle  of  knowledge,  as  the 
true  end  for  man's  endeavour,  he  is  really  struggling  toward  it.  And 
at  last,  in  the  dialogues  of  the  final  period,  he  brings  it  to  explicit 
utterance.  But  yet  he  does  not  enter  into  full  possession  of  it  as  the 
instrument  for  the  rational  comprehension  of  the  world;  one  great 
province  or  aspect  of  the  world  he  to  the  end  leaves  outside.  He  is 
unable  to  come  to  a  view  of  the  whole  process  of  the  universe  as  an 
evolution,  in  and  through  which  the  supreme  reason,  by  communicating 
itself,  realises  its  purpose;  rather,  he  tends  to  the  end  to  break  the 
continuity  between  the  real  world,  as  a  realm  of  fixed  and  complete 
perfections,  and  this  present  world,  where  nothing  is,  but  everything 
with  imperfection  and  sorrow  is  becoming.  There  must  be,  he  knows, 
some  connexion  between  the  two.  But  he  feels  that  the  connexion  is 
not  continuous,  not  fully  organic.  Something  which  is  a  radical 
opponent  of  reality  has  intervened  to  break  the  continuity;  and  how 
that  can  be,  he  explains  by  the  supposition  that  when  the  divine  nature 
went  forth  upon  its  creative  activity  it  worked  in  a  region  or  upon  a 
medium  which  was  alien  and  intractable,  so  that  the  divine  nature 

252 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

could  not  do  itself  justice  in  its  own  creation;  or  rather  its  creation 
is  not  altogether  its  own,  Necessity  or  non-being  having  also  a  part 
in  it. 

In  Plato,  then,  if  one  may  so  speak,  Idealism. reached  its  goal,  but 
did  not  quite  enter  into  possession  of  it.  In  this  sense,  Plato's  was  a 
philosophy  that  called  upon  the  later  world  to  complete  it.  And, 
whether  with  or  without  conscious  reference  to  Plato,  the  later  world 
took  up  the  task.  Indeed,  one  might  almost  say  that  the  history  of 
Idealism  falls  into  two  great  chapters :  the  first,  the  story  of  its  founda 
tion  by  Plato ;  the  second,  the  longer  and  more  perplexed  story  of  how 
the  philosophy  thus  founded  entered  into  clearer  possession  of  its  own 
highest  conception,  and  so  became  better  able  to  do  justice  to  its  view 
of  the  world  as  an  order  of  reason  and  of  righteousness. 

As  soon  as  we  pass  the  limits  of  the  purely  Greek  age,  that 
second  chapter  in  the  history  of  Idealism  becomes  infinitely  com 
plicated.  First,  indeed,  there  comes  a  complete  triumph  of  the 
opposite  tendency — in  the  mystic  theology  and  religion  which  had 
their  most  congenial  home  in  Alexandria.  And  from  that  time  on, 
the  whole  breadth  and  complexity  of  the  history  of  the  world  enters 
into  the  history  of  Idealism.  The  rest  of  this  book  is  to  be  given  to 
a  consideration  of  two  single  points  in  that  history,  which,  however 
small  a  part  they  form  of  the  total  history,  are  yet  sufficient 
to  show  the  breadth,  the  depth,  the  vitality,  the  complexity,  of  the 
forces  that  worked  there.  But  before  we  go  on  to  that,  a  moment 
should  be  given  to  the  question  which  meets  us  upon  the  threshold 
of  what  has  just  been  called  the  "  second  chapter  "  in  the  history  of 
idealistic  philosophy.  What  advance  in  the  direction  of  making 
Idealism  more  concrete  by  further  articulating  its  highest  conception, 
was  made  within  the  age  of  Hellenic  thought?  Without  considering 
this  question,  on  the  one  hand  the  attempt  to  understand  Plato  is  left 
half-finished,  while,  on  the  other  hand,  factors  that  worked  in  the  later 
history  are  neglected.  So  that  at  least  a  brief  reference  must  be 
made  here,  first  to  Aristotle,  secondly  to  the  Stoics. 

Aristotle,  after  insisting — in  fact,  over-insisting — upon  the  dualism 
in  Plato,  strikes  directly  into  the  pathway  which  leads  toward  the 
overcoming  of  it ;  or  rather,  which  excludes  it  from  the  beginning. 

253  :£2 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

For  he  comes  to  his  constructive  work  with  the  insight  that  the  real 
world  consists  of  formed  matter;  that  is  to  say,  of  concrete  individ 
uals.  And  concerning  the  individual  things  and  beings  which  thus 
make  up  the  world,  two  facts  are  clear.  First,  the  universals  which 
realise  themselves  in  these  individuals,  do  so  only  gradually.  Individ 
ual  things  are  not  eternally  or  changelessly  themselves.  They  come 
to  be  themselves;  they  pass  from  potentiality  to  actuality.  Secondly, 
the  individual  things  of  the  world  do  not  stand  upon  a  level.  They 
form  a  scale  of  being,  which  is  the  system  of  the  universe;  a  scale  in 
which  each  individual  is  actuality  to  those  below  it,  but  matter  or 
potentiality  to  those  above.  So  that  the  universe  is  one  great  life  or 
process,  in  the  survey  of  which  we  are  led  upward  from  mere  matter 
or  potentiality  to  the  realisation  of  ever  higher  universals.  But 
secondly,  in  this  movement  from  potentiality  to  actuality — whether 
we  think  merely  of  the  formation  of  some  individual  thing,  or  of  the 
total  movement  which  is  the  process  of  the  universe — there  is  always  a 
priority  of  the  actual  to  the  potential.  And  that  in  knowledge,  in 
time,  and  in  substance.  In  knowledge;  for  it  is  only  by  seeing  the 
actuality  which  a  given  thing  may  become  that  I  am  in  position  to 
view  that  given  thing  as  potentiality  at  all.  In  time;  just  as  the 
finished  house  in  the  architect's  thought  must  precede  the  shaping  of 
the  separate  timbers  and  stones,  or  as  the  fully  completed  growth  of 
corn  must  precede  the  corn  which  is  used  as  seed.  In  substance; 
because  the  end  which  a  process  is  to  realise  is  the  true  governing 
principle  of  the  process;  because,  in  other  words,  the  rtXo*  of  a 
process  is  its  true  apxrj7  its  final  cause  its  true  efficient  cause. 

So  far,  then,  we  have  seen  (1)  that  the  process  of  the  universe  is  a 
process  of  movement  upward  from  potentiality  to  actuality ;  ( 2 )  that 
to  the  existence  and  continuance  of  such  a  process,  there  is  necessary 
a  priority  of  the  actual  to  the  potential.  But  these  two  insights  at  once 
set  a  further  problem:  What  is  that  actuality  which  is  the  prius  of 
this  whole  system — this  whole  continuous  and  eternal  world-process — 
of  potentialities  and  actualities  ?  That  prius  must  be  eternal ;  must  be 
self-active  energy;  must  be  actuality  fully-realised  and  perfect — 
actuality  without  any  mixture  of  unactualised  potentiality;  must,  in 
a  word,  be  an  eternal  and  self-dependent  principle,  which,  by  its  very 

254 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

nature,  energises  perfectly  and  to  the  full  height  of  being.  But  how 
is  such  an  energy  to  be  conceived  ?  This  Aristotle  answers  by  his  great 
conception  of  self -consciousness.  That  fully-realised  actuality  which 
is  implied  in  the  process  of  the  world,  is  an  eternal  and  completely 
actualised  reason  which  has  itself  for  its  object. 

Here  we  seem  on  the  very  verge  of  the  completion  of  Idealism, 
with  regard  at  least  to  the  system  of  its  conceptions.  But  there  is 
still  a  question  to  ask.  That  eternal  self-consciousness,  completely 
actualised  and  perfect,  having  in  its  own  activity  its  adequate  object : — 
will  Aristotle  describe  it  as  the  creative  and  informing  energy  of  the 
whole  process  of  the  world,  so  that  the  world  is  its  thought,  its 
activity,  its  objective  consciousness,  and  it,  as  at  once  transcendent 
and  immanent,  is  the  source  and  the  explanation,  the  home  and  the 
end,  of  the  world? 

If  Aristotle  could  have  done  this,  he  would  have  brought  his  great 
argument  to  its  consistent  conclusion;  would  have  done  justice  at 
once  to  his  principle  that  universal  and  particular  must  not  be 
separated,  and  to  the  call  which  his  criticism  of  Plato  makes  upon 
himself ;  would  have  brought  Greek  thinking  to  its  culmination  in  an 
Idealism  of  thoroughly  concrete  type.  And  at  times — for  instance,  in 
his  comparison  of  the  order  of  the  universe  to  the  order  of  an  army — 
he  does  seem  to  put  into  express  words  precisely  such  a  conclusion. 
But  though  his  whole  argument  calls  for  such  a  conclusion  and 
prepares  the  way  for  it,  yet  he  cannot  be  said  clearly  and  unwaver 
ingly  to  hold  it.  For  his  own  view  of  what  reason  is  in  its  perfect 
exercise,  lies  in  the  way.  Eeason,  he  sees,  to  be  perfect,  must  supply 
to  itself  its  own  object.  If  it  receives  its  object  from  without,  the 
result  must  be,  in  the  case  of  the  supreme  reason  of  the  universe,  the 
intrusion  of  something  non-rational.  Of  that  supreme  reason  we  must, 
therefore,  believe  that  it  is  absolutely  self-contained,  supplying  its  own 
object,  depending  on  nothing  from  without.  While  reason  as  it  is  in 
man  must  be  regarded  as  a  sort  of  combination  in  which  an  active 
element,  corresponding  to  the  divine  reason,  somehow  goes  along  with 
a  passive  element  which  is  connected  with  the  body  and  its  avenues  of 
sense. 

The  view  that  the  self-consciousness  which  is  the  supreme  reason 

255 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

of  the  universe,  must  be  complete  within  itself,  supplying  its  own 
object,  is  perfectly  sound;  might,  in  fact,  be  called  an  axiom.  But 
it  does  not  forbid  the  view  of  Concrete  or  Positive  Idealism  that  the 
universe  is  the  objective  consciousness  of  God.  Aristotle,  however, 
takes  it  precisely  so  as  to  forbid  that  conclusion.  Like  Plato,  he  is 
acutely  conscious  of  the  imperfection  of  the  world  of  our  sense- 
experience.  It  certainly  must  be  excluded,  he  feels,  from  that  system 
of  absolutely  perfect  reason  which  alone  can  form  the  objective 
consciousness  of  God.  So  that  in  his  conception  of  God,  and  of  the 
relation  of  the  sense-world  to  Him,  Aristotle  is  really  more  Platonic 
than  that  very  side  of  Plato  against  which  his  severest  criticisms  had 
been  directed.  God's  existence  is  perfect  peace,  exalted  above  all 
change  and  becoming.  He  is  active  intelligence,  but  His  activity 
cannot  be  viewed  as  the  carrying  on  of  any  such  process  of  develop 
ment  as  the  world,  nor  can  His  intelligence  have  a  world  of  change 
as  its  object.  Eather  His  activity  is  one  absolutely  free  from 
potentiality  or  becoming,  and  His  knowledge  one  which  can  have  no 
other  object  than  Himself  as  perfect  being  and  absolute  truth.  He  is 
altogether  self-contained;  His  blessedness  consists  precisely  in  that 
knowledge  in  which,  as  absolute  subject,  He  has  Himself  as  His  own 
perfect  and  adequate  object: — a  blessedness  which  would  lose  its 
perfection,  its  peace,  its  exaltation  above  all  change,  if  the  divine 
activity  went  forth  into  any  such  world  as  that  of  our  daily  struggle, 
or  the  divine  nature  manifested  itself  in  any  process  of  becoming. 
God  in  His  blessedness  is  a  universe  by  Himself,  complete,  eternal, 
perfect.  But  the  world  of  our  experience,  which  the  whole  inquiry 
was  undertaken  to  explain,  and  which  up  to  this  point  it  did  explain, 
is  here  at  one  stroke  severed  from  its  own  ultimate  principle.  Steadily 
the  great  argument  had  been  carried  forward.  It  had  been  shown 
that  the  process  of  development  from  potentiality  to  actuality  which 
is  the  world,  involves  as  its  necessary  prius  an  actuality,  eternal,  self- 
active,  having  in  it  no  unrealised  potentiality;  and  that  this  can  be 
conceived  only  as  self-consciousness,  only  as  a  completely  actualised 
reason.  But  when  it  remains  only  to  put  the  capstone  upon  the  whole 
argument  by  saying  that  God  is  the  creative  and  constitutive  energy 
of  the  world,  and  that  it  is  through  His  communication  of  Himself 

256 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

that  individual  things  have  natures  and  capacities  of  their  own,  and  so 
are  able  to  exist  and  energise  and  fill  their  places  in  the  system  of  the 
world : — precisely  then  it  is  that  Aristotle,  in  the  way  which  we  have 
just  seen,  is  led  to  turn  round  upon  his  own  argument,  and  to  give  it 
a  conclusion  opposite  to  that  which  its  whole  previous  course  had 
called  for. 

Thus,  then,  the  Aristotelian  vo^ffis  vor'jGeoos — the  conception  of 
the  supreme  principle  of  reality  as  self-consciousness — does  not  lead  to 
a  view  of  the  organic  connexion  of  God,  as  the  concrete  and  all- 
inclusive  universal,  with  the  world,  and  with  that  process  of  develop 
ment  which  is  the  history  of  the  world.  Not,  indeed,  that  Aristotle 
evades  the  problem  of  the  relation  between  God  and  the  world.  But 
he  tends  to  make  it  a  relation  altogether  from  the  world's  side.  As  a 
lover  moves  toward  a  beautiful  and  beloved  object,  and  is  governed  by 
the  impulse  to  organise  his  life  according  to  its  form  and  nature,  so 
the  world  moves  toward  God.  In  this  sense,  indeed,  God,  as  the  end 
toward  which  the  world  moves  and  which  it  seeks  to  realise,  is  the 
governing  principle  of  the  whole  process  of  the  world.  But  not 
through  any  activity  on  the  part  of  God  Himself.  His  activity  can 
be  no  other  than  that  of  absolutely  pure  thought;  and  the  object  of 
such  thought  can  be  nothing  other  than  the  perfect  reason  which  is 
Himself.  In  that  contemplation  He  remains,  perfect  and  unchange 
able  in  blessedness  for  ever.1 

Aristotle's  view  of  what  constitutes  reason  in  its  perfect  exercise, 
coupled  with  his  sense  of  the  imperfection  of  the  world  of  our  sensible 
experience,  was  decisive,  then,  of  the  character  of  his  Idealism.  In 
fact,  his  conception  of  reason  was  determinative,  as  the  Master  of 
Balliol  reminds  us,2  in  all  the  great  departments  of  his  thought.  In 

1  See,  however,  Caird,  The  Evolution  of  Theology  in  the  Greek  Philosophers,  vol.  II., 
pp.  11-30.    Between  the  two  interpretations,  there  is  no  difference  with  regard  to  the 
broad  fact  that  Aristotle  makes  a  virtually  complete  disjunction  between  God  and  the 
present  world  of  change  and  contingency.    The  point  in  dispute  is  whether  the  line  is 
drawn  above  or  below  the  universals  which  are  seeking  to  realise  themselves  in  the 
things  of  the  world— above  or  below  what  Plato  would  have  called  the  Ideas.    In  other 
words,  is  the  object  of  the  divine  thought,  the  universals  as  a  system  of  absolutely  pure 
reason,  lifted  above  all  change  and  contingency,  or  is  it  God  Himself  in  a  sense  which 
excludes  these  ?    On  the  former  view,  the  step  to  an  organic  theory  would  be  much  easier. 
But,  whether  easy  or  hard,  Aristotle  does  not  take  it.    In  the  present  world  he  continues  to 
recognise  a  contingency  with  which  neither  God  nor  pure  reason  can  have  any  connexion. 

2  The  Evolution  of  Theology  in  the  Greek  Philosophers,  vol.  I.,  p.  287  seq. 
18  257 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

his  ethic  it  leads  him  to  rank  the  Intellectual  Virtues  in  which  reason 
deals  purely  with  itself,  above  the  Practical  Virtues  in  which  reason 
is  in  relation  with  a  world  of  sense  and  change.  In  his  psychology  it 
leads  to  a  disjunction  of  the  two  aspects  of  man's  intelligence.  There 
is  a  reason,,  eternal  and  existing  separately,  which  makes  all  things. 
And  there  is  a  passive  or  receptive  reason  in  man,  which  becomes  all 
things.  This,  indeed,  might  seem  a  convenient  form  for  working  out 
an  organic  connexion  between  the  universal  principles  of  the  world 
and  the  particulars  of  our  ordinary  experience.  But  the  connexion 
of  the  two  reasons  in  man  seems  after  all  to  be  only  an  external  one; 
at  the  death  of  the  body  it  is  dissolved,  passive  reason  perishing  with 
the  body  in  relation  to  which  it  existed,  active  reason  continuing  in 
that  independent  and  unmixed  existence  which  either  is,  or  is  like,  the 
divine  existence.  And  of  the  disjunction  which  thus  runs  through 
every  part  of  his  system,  the  separation  of  God  and  the  world  which 
we  have  just  been  considering  is  simply  the  highest  and  final  instance. 
It  will  be  noticed  that  the  logical  motives  of  the  dualism  which 
thus  remains  in  Aristotle,  are  the  same  as  those  we  saw  operative  in 
Plato's  thought;  only  Aristotle  draws  the  lines  more  rigidly.  Like 
Plato,  Aristotle  was  keenly  alive  to  the  imperfection  of  the  world.  In 
it  he  found  something  essentially  non-rational — an  irreducible  and 
intractable  contingency,  corresponding  to  that  necessity  of  which 
Plato  had  spoken  in  the  Timaeus.  And  in  each  case,  this  works  in  at 
once  with  the  very  natural  conception  that  since  the  highest  principle 
of  reality  is  absolutely  perfect,  it  cannot  be  conceived  as  working 
through,  or  in,  any  media  except  those  that  have  an  absolute  perfection 
like  its  own;  which  means  for  Aristotle  that  in  spite  of  his  own 
conception  of  evolution  as  a  way  of  nature,  he  cannot  conceive  it  as  a 
way  of  God.  That  for  created  beings  the  only  genuine  perfection  is 
one  in  whose  achieving  they  themselves  have  co-operated,  and  that 
therefore  the  divine  creative  activity  must  begin  with  something  less 
than  perfection: — this  is  an  argument  which  Aristotle  cannot  admit. 
He  sees  the  imperfection  of  the  world;  sees  the  imperfection  of  our 
experience  in  it ;  but  cannot  conceive  of  God  as  working  through  such 
imperfection  toward  that  true  perfection  which  is  wrought  out  only 
in  struggle.  God  as  perfect  must  be  self-contained  in  the  sense  of 

258 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

excluding  the  world  of  change;  as  complete  actuality,  having  in 
Himself  no  unrealised  potentiality  at  all,  He  cannot  have  an  object 
lower  than  Himself,  nor  any  activity  lower  than  the  contemplation 
of  absolute  perfection;  the  world  of  becoming,  while  it  may  be 
impelled  by  the  inner  principle  of  its  life  to  move  for  ever  toward  Him, 
cannot  be  His  workmanship  nor  the  temple  of  His  indwelling. 
Indeed,  in  view  of  this  similarity  in  the  inner  logic  of  their  systems, 
one  may  almost  say  that  the  difference  between  Plato  and  Aristotle  is 
one  rather  of  temper  and  manner  than  of  fundamental  logical  motives 
or  of  ultimate  conclusions.  Aristotle  works  his  way  outward  from  his 
Idealistic  centre  to  a  great  cyclopaedia  of  natural  and  social  science 
illuminated  by  Idealistic  conceptions.  But  while  Aristotle  thus 
delights  to  work  upon  the  circumference  even  at  the  expense  of 
occasionally  forgetting  the  centre,  Plato  prefers  to  remain  habitually 
at  the  centre,  and  only  from  its  lofty  height  to  view  the  circumference. 
Hence  Plato  frequently  tends — under  the  influence  of  the  Par- 
menidean  cast  and  tendency  which  remained  in  his  many-sided 
intellect  even  after  he  had  overcome  the  specifically  Parmenidean 
argument,  and  under  the  influence  still  more  of  the  lofty  religious 
ness  native  to  his  character  and  deepened  by  grief  and  by  high  hope 
disappointed — to  put  the  whole  of  the  emphasis  upon  the  centre  and 
despise  or  even  deny  the  circumference;  thus  really  breaking  the 
unity  of  his  system  through  the  very  intensity  of  his  instinct  for  that 
unity.  While  Aristotle,  with  his  cooler  scientific  mind,  gives  attention 
to  both  centre  and  circumference,  and  yet  wrongs  both  by  setting  them 
apart. 

So  far,  then,  for  the  first  step  in  the  history  of  Idealism  after 
Plato.  Aristotle,  seeing  the  defect  in  the  Platonic  Idealism,  and 
pointing  out  the  way  to  overcome  it,  ends  by  retaining  it ;  ends  with 
the  conception,  not  of  a  God  who  is  the  life  of  the  world,  and  of  a 
world  which  is  the  activity  and  manifestation  of  God,  but  of  a  world 
which  has  life  in  itself,  and  a  God  who  dwells  apart  from  it  in  the 
solitude  of  absolute  perfection,  in  the  blessedness  of  a  contemplation 
in  which  a  perfect  subject  gazes  for  ever  upon  a  perfect  object. 

With  Aristotle  we  are  really  at  the  end  of  strictly  Hellenic 
thought.  Already  the  wide  world  was  breaking  in  upon  Greece  and 

259 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

another  age  was  preparing.  But  before  we  pass  on  to  it,  we  must  give 
a  moment  to  the  men  who  did  so  much  in  that  preparation  for  it — the 
Stoics.  These,  though  their  first  interest  was  practical — the  search 
for  a  wise  way  of  living — were  genuinely  great  in  metaphysic; 
indeed,  without  being  so,  they  could  not  have  been  great  in  ethics.  In 
metaphysic,  however,  the  "  root  of  the  matter  "  is  in  a  sense  twofold. 
There  is  first  the  instinct  for  the  unity  of  all  existence ;  but,  secondly, 
the  instinct  for  doing  justice  to  the  individual  existences  within  that 
unity  and  to  the  particular  facts  which  make  .up  the  life  of  these. 
Without  the  first  there  is  nothing  worthy  of  being  called  philosophy ; 
but  the  second  must  work  with  it  to  do  justice  to  the  wealth  which 
the  unity  really  contains.  Now,  the  Stoics  were  weak  in  the  lesser 
matters — and  therefore  in  many  of  the  greater  matters — of  the  second. 
But  they  were  victoriously  strong  in  the  first.  Platonic  and  Aristo 
telian  dualism  they  sweep  out  at  one  stroke.  They  have  no  doubt  at  all 
that  reality  is  one — and  that  it  is  rational;  no  doubt  at  all  that  the 
supreme  principle  of  reality  is  immanent  in  the  world,  and  that  it  is 
kindred  in  nature  to  the  reason  which  is  in  man;  no  doubt  at  all  that 
man  is  capable  of  communion  with  it  and  of  obedience  to  its  ways,  and 
that  in  that  communion  and  obedience  lie  his  freedom  and  his  true 
way  of  life. 

This  seems  a  great  advance.  And  in  one  sense  it  is  a  great 
advance.  Yet  we  must  make  clear  to  ourselves  what  it  does,  and  what 
it  does  not,  contain.  It  is  not  enough  to  assert  the  true  conclusion, 
unless  you  make  it  intelligible;  not  enough  to  assert  that  reality  is 
one,  unless  you  show  how  it  is  one.  And  this  the  Stoics  were  not  in 
position  to  do ;  were  far  less  in  position  to  do  than  Plato  or  Aristotle. 
Still  less  than  Plato  or  Aristotle  had  they  proceeded  from  an  appre 
hension  of  the  reason  in  man  as  a  synthetic  principle — from  that 
apprehension  which  led  Kant  to  the  emphatic  statement  about  man's 
understanding  that  it  "  makes  nature/'  And  without  this  they  might 
assert  the  rationality  of  the  whole  system  and  structure  of  the 
universe;  but  they  could  not  articulate  that  insight.  And  such 
articulation  is  the  business  of  systematic  philosophy. 

So  that  in  the  metaphysic  of  the  Stoics  we  have  to  mark  a  double 
defect,  each  side  of  which  intensifies  the  other.  They  despised  and 

260 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

rejected  certain  aspects  of  experience.,  certain  provinces  of  reality. 
And,  holding  the  view  that  the  world  is  rational,  they  could  not  give 
to  that  view  its  systematic  articulation.  But  of  course  it  is  to  be 
remembered  that  the  true  Stoic  was  first  of  all  a  soldier  of  righteous 
ness,  and  only  secondarily  a  philosopher  of  the  school.  He  fought  in 
the  most  cruel  of  all  moral  conflicts — that  which  arises  from  the  decay 
of  a  great  civilisation.  Simplicity  and  uprightness  seemed  to  be  gone 
from  the  earth,  luxury  and  wickedness  everywhere  to  prevail.  By 
nothing  less  than  a  general  treason  of  society,  the  causes  of  right 
reason  stood  defeated.  Upon  the  field  of  that  lost  battle,  the  Stoic 
lived  his  life;  and  as  the  shadows  of  night  grew  deeper,  and  the 
hideous  forms  that  thrive  in  its  darkness  gathered  more  thickly 
around,  he  recognised  it  as  his  vocation  to  form  no  other  ties  than 
those  of  his  soldier's  duty,  and  to  stand  immovable  at  the  post  to  which 
the  wisdom  of  the  universe  had  assigned  him. 

Aristotle,  then,  holds  that  the  highest  reality  is  a  self-conscious 
and  self-dependent  spirit,  existing  separately  from  our  world  of 
change ;  while  the  Stoic  holds  precisely  the  complementary  view,  that 
God  is  immanent  in  the  world  as  its  reason  and  its  life.  But  Greek 
thought  was  not  able  to  work  out,  as  a  clearly  articulated  possession  of 
the  scientific  mind,  the  conception  which,  by  taking  up  both  those  sides 
into  the  unity  of  a  more  comprehensive  view,  would  have  enabled  each 
of  them  to  enter  into  its  own  proper  significance  and  to  unite  with  the 
other.  That  conception  is  not  merely  the  conception  of  God  as  self- 
conscious  and,  self-dependent  spirit,  but  the  further  conception  of  Him 
as  the  self-conscious  and  self-determining  spirit  who  is  the  subject  of 
the  world ;  so  that  the  world  is  regarded  as  an  activity  or  manifesta 
tion  of  God,  the  history  of  the  world  as  a  process  in  which  a  divine 
purpose  is  being  realised ;  that  purpose,  again,  not  being  arbitrarily  or 
externally  chosen,  but  arising  out  of  and  expressing  the  divine  nature 
itself,  and  being  capable  of  fulfilment,  therefore,  only  by  the  gradual 
impartation  of  the  divine  mind  and  nature  to  man.  For  such  an 
Idealism  Greek  thought  assembled  the  materials;  but  scarcely  was 
able  to  bring  them  to  the  unity  of  an  organic  structure.  This  was  to 
some  extent  a  matter  simply  of  the  order  of  time.  In  the  history  of 

261 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

thought  it  is  a  conspicuous  and  much  honoured  part  to  set  in  place 
the  keystone  which  makes  visible  to  all  the  world  the  unity  of  the 
manifold  building  and  of  the  varied  labours  that  have  entered  into  it. 
But  first  must  come  the  more  heroic  workmen  who,  with  only  the 
prophetic  instinct  of  science  to  guide  them,  lay  deep  foundations  at 
what  seem  hopeless  distances  apart.  And  then,  too,  a  fully  developed 
Idealism  requires  an  historical  outlook  such  as  was  not  possible  to  the 
Greeks ;  an  outlook  over  successive  ages  and  races,  each  doing  its  work 
upon  the  earth  and  passing  away,  and  thus  setting  the  mind  of  the 
spectator  upon  the  search  for  some  plan  of  the  world  or  wisdom  of 
history.  And  there  was  still  another  reason;  one  connected,  not 
simply  with  the  historical  position  of  the  Greeks,  but  with  the  intrinsic 
quality  of  their  mind.  As  we  have  seen,  Idealism  arises  when,  seeking 
to  know  the  world,  you  also  know  the  soul  and  find  in  it  a  principle  for 
interpreting  the  world.  For  the  place  where  we  apprehend  the  char 
acter  of  spirit  as  an  active  principle  of  synthesis,  is  in  ourselves. 
Unless  we  have  apprehended  the  nature  and  activity  of  spirit  there,  we 
cannot  be  in  position  to  articulate  clearly  and  consistently  the  insight 
that  spirit  is  the  principle  of  synthesis,  the  constitutive  and  organising 
energy,  implied  in  the  existence  of  the  universe.  But  the  Hellenic 
mind,  while  devoted  to  the  objective  interests  of  the  spirit,  was  disin 
clined  to  set  the  individual  soul  before  it  in  order  to  analyse  its  inner 
processes  for  their  own  sake.  The  strength,  the  intellectual  tact,  the 
unfailing  clearness,  of  the  Greek  genius,  were  based  in  a  certain  large 
and  calm  objectivity,  a  tendency  to  fix  contemplation  upon  that 
universal  structure  of  things  which  was  felt  to  be  at  once  more  real 
and  more  worthy  than  the  single  soul  in  its  individuality.  And  this 
objective  tendency  of  the  Hellenic  mind  was  the  source  at  once  of  the 
greatness  and  the  incompleteness  of  Greek  Idealism. 

But  this  indicates  to  us  in  what  direction  we  must  look,  if  we 
would  see  the  Idealistic  or  spiritual  view  of  the  world  completing  itself 
from  within.  We  must  look  fof  an  age,  or  a  type  of  experience,  in 
which  the  individual  soul  becomes  a  thing  of  supreme  value,  and,  in  a 
profound  and  worthy  sense  (i.e.,  without  sinking  into  mere  subjectiv 
ism,  without  losing  objectivity  of  view  and  of  interest)  is  turned  in 
upon  itself.  And  precisely  such  a  type  of  experience  was  now  to 

262 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

become  the  chief  factor  of  human  history,  in  a  religion  which,  so  far 
as  it  could  be  faithful  to  the  whole  of  itself,  did  not  turn  its  eyes  away 
from  the  world,  and  yet  was  a  religion  of  the  inner  spirit;  a  religion 
in  which  the  struggles  and  attainments  of  the  inner  spirit  are  viewed 
as  the  most  real  thing  in  life,  and  therefore  as  that  in  the  world  which 
most  truly  expresses  the  nature  and  meaning  of  the  world. 

II. 

Such  a  religion — a  religion  that  from  the  inner  spirit  goes  forth 
to  the  world  and  to  the  whole  breadth  of  the  interests  of  the  world — 
was  Christianity;  Christianity,  at  least,  as  it  existed  in  the  mind  of 
its  Founder,  or  as  it  struggles  in  human  society  to  be  faithful  to  that 
mind.  Jesus,  in  His  daily  life  and  habitual  consciousness,  looked  upon 
those  eternal  relations  of  man's  life  which  are  the  order  and  structure 
of  the  universe,  with  an  objectivity  as  large,  as  calm,  as  unfailing,  as 
that  of  the  Greek  mind  itself;  and  looking  thus  upon  them,  He 
expressed  them  in  terms  of  the  spirit.  He  searched  the  inner  spirit; 
but  he  did  not  shut  men  up  to  it.  Freely  He  looked  upon  the  world ; 
freely,  turning  His  eyes  away  from  nothing,  He  regarded  the  whole 
order  and  structure  of  it,  the  whole  constitution  of  things  in  which 
man  lives,  the  whole  array  of  the  conditions  of  our  life.1  And  as  He 
looked  with  this  clear  and  open  gaze  upon  the  world,  not  all  its  imper 
fection,  not  all  its  evil,  could  make  Him  waver  for  a  single  instant  in 
His  consciousness  that  the  relations  which  constitute  its  order  and  the 
order  of  man's  life,  are  ultimately  spiritual,  ultimately  moral — nay, 
immediately  spiritual,  immediately  moral.  His  consciousness  of  God 
He  habitually  expressed  in  the  words,  My  Father;  His  consciousness 
of  the  relation  of  God  to  the  human  world  and  of  the  human  world  to 
God,  in  the  words,  Our  Father.  Man's  life,  that  is  to  say,  is  a  com 
munication  of  Himself  on  the  part  of  God;  the  universe,  a  society  of 
spirits  which  God  constitutes  and  administers  as  His  family.  With 

1  Even  with  "nature"  in  the  more  restricted  sense  of  the  word— the  external  world, 
the  birds  and  fields  and  lilies— He  lived  as  a  man  might  live  with  the  things  of  His  home 
(see  Caird,  The  Evolution  of  Religion,  vol.  II.,  p.  122  seq.).  It  would  indicate  a  truth, 
were  one  to  say  that  the  view  which  Wordsworth  took  of  nature  poetically,  Jesus  took 
religiously. 

263 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

Him  and  with  the  ultimate  realities  of  eternity  we  all  stand  in 
intimate  organic  relationship :  whatsoever  we  do  to  "  the  least  of 
these,"  we  do  to  Jesus  and  therefore  to  the  Father;  or  again,  to 
choose  an  instance  of  a  different  character,  Jesus  habitually  speaks  of 
eternal  life  as  a  present  possession. 

And  of  such  a  view  of  the  world  as  a  system  over  the  whole  of 
which  the  love,  the  righteousness,  the  wisdom,  of  the  Father  extend, 
"  reaching  from  end  to  end,  sweetly  and  strongly  ordering  all  things," 
— of  such  a  view  the  practical  attitude  of  Jesus  was,  if  possible,  even 
more  expressive  than  His  words.  He  lived  a  life  of  absolute  confidence 
in  the  Father:  absolute  confidence  in  the  Father's  administration  of 
the  world ;  absolute  confidence  in  the  reach  of  that  administration  over 
every  side  of  man's  life,  over  every  aspect  of  the  world  and  of  its 
history;  absolute  confidence  in  the  supremacy  of  the  Father  and  in 
the  inability  of  any  power  to  defeat  His  purpose ;  absolute  confidence, 
therefore,  in  the  good,  and  in  the  impossibility  that  any  labour  for 
the  good  can  ultimately  be  without  its  due  effect.  This  confidence  in 
the  Father  who  "  sends  us,"  and  in  the  good  which  is  His  purpose, 
was  the  habitual  mind  of  Jesus.  He  saw  human  life  as  human  life 
actually  is ;  He  faced  all  the  sufferings  of  men,  all  the  sins  of  men,  all 
the  sinfulness  of  men,  and  never  lost  hope,  or  fell  into  bitterness,  or 
held  back  in  misgiving ;  but  remained  absolutely  certain  that  through 
all  this  stricken  and  troubled  process  of  the  world's  history  omnipotent 
goodness  is  at  work  realising  its  purpose.  Hence  He  taught  that  the 
man  who  really  saves  his  life  is  the  man  who  loses  it  by  devoting 
himself  to  that  divine  purpose  and  making  himself  its  organ  ;*  and  He 
gave  to  His  belief  in  the  organic  relation  of  the  human  world  to  God 
the  most  decisive  of  all  possible  expressions,  by  seeking  to  win  men's 
hearts  and  to  lead  them  toward  a  consciousness  of  God  similar  to  His 
own  and  toward  the  way  of  life  which  arises  from  such  a  consciousness. 

Such  a  confidence  in  God,  such  a  belief  in  the  possible  unity  of  the 
affairs  of  the  world  with  the  divine  plan,  it  was  that  Christianity 
carried  with  it,  as  it  went  out  to  be  the  religion  of  the  world. 
Implicitly — not  as  a  possession  of  the  intellect,  but  as  an  inner  spirit 
of  faith  and  of  life — it  held  the  view  that  the  world  and  the  history  of 

i  See  Caird,  The  Evolution  of  Religion,  vol.  II.,  pp.  88,  104-5,  137. 
264 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

the  world  stand  in  organic  connexion  with  the  ultimate  God.  But 
Christianity  was  certain  to  come  more  and  more  to  intellectual 
possession  of  its  implicit  faith.  For  the  world  out  into  which  it  went 
was  that  Gentile  world  which  had  inherited  the  intellectual  spirit  of 
the  Greeks,,  and  their  impulse  to  bring  implicit  beliefs  to  the  light  of 
day  in  the  form  of  ordered  science.1 

But  the  history  of  this  entrance  of  Christendom  upon  the  intel 
lectual  possession  of  its  own  implicit  view  of  God  and  the  world,  is 
perhaps  the  most  complicated  of  all  human  histories.  In  the  first 
place,  there  is  a  complexity  from  within.  Christianity  could  scarcely 
advance  immediately  to  the  apprehension  of  the  organic  connexion  of 
God  and  the  world.  It  was  inevitable  that  the  advance  should  be,  in  a 
sense,  dialectic ;  should  be  an  advance  through  antithesis  to  synthesis. 
For  Christianity  has  in  it  the  possibility  of  both  the  forms  of  the 
religious  temper  distinguished  on  a  previous  page.2  With  the  acute 
sensitiveness  to  all  evil,  the  imperious  consciousness  of  sin,  which  it 
introduces  into  life,  it  tends,  both  with  individuals  and  the  church,  to 
assume  at  the  beginning  the  more  negative  of  the  two  forms.  Under 
this  form,  it  leads  men  to  condemn  not  only  their  sins  and  their  sinful 
tendencies,  but  the  whole  of  their  nature  and  the  whole  of  the  world. 
Thus  it  becomes  a  principle  of  separation  from  the  world ;  and  to  the 
negative  implied  in  its  positive  gives  so  great  a  place  as  to  obscure  or 
even  defeat  that  positive  itself.  Such  religion,  too,  is  commonly  the 
religion  of  intense  natures.  Hence,  when  it  gains  hold  upon  the 
church,  it  is  as  a  rule  only  slowly  and  with  struggle  that  the  advance 
beyond  it  is  made.  Soon  or  late,  however,  the  advance  must  come. 
For,  in  that  form,  Christianity,  though  an  intense  and  heroic  religion, 
is  involved  in  a  deep  contradiction  with  itself,  with  the  mind  of  its 
founder,  and  with  reason.  It  cannot  see  the  world  as  a  work  of  God ; 
and  instead  of  saving  it,  leaves  it  to  those  of  its  powers  which  are  most 
unlike  God.  Its  inner  principle,  that  is  to  say,  is  working  under 

1  Hence  it  is  strikingly  appropriate  that  the  man  who  formally  completed  Idealism  in 
its  Platonic -type,  was  a  Father  of  the  church— Augustine,  who  on  one  of  the  many  sides 
of  his  intense  and  eager  thought,  made  the  Ideas  (the  norms  upon  which  human  thinking 
proceeds,  but  which  manifestly  go  beyond  the  individual  mind,  and  have  a  universal 
validity)  to  be  forms  or  standards  in  the  divine  mind. 

2  Supra,  pp.  221,  222. 

265 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

limitations  which  contradict  that  inner  principle  itself.  Hence  the 
forces  which  make  for  human  development,  continually  impel  that 
principle  to  fulfil  itself  by  going  beyond  those  limitations.  Keason, 
which  is  irreconcilably  an  enemy  to  Manichseism;  experience,  which 
shows  how  genuinely  great  are  the  world  and  the  natural  mind  of 
man ;  the  love  which  carries  the  individual  beyond  himself  and  beyond 
the  limits  of  his  church  or  order  to  the  service  of  the  imperfect  world ; 
the  mind  of  the  Founder,  exerting  itself  in  the  church : — these  produce 
gradually  their  effect,  and  the  mind  of  Christendom  comes  more  and 
more  to  apprehend  that  the  world  stands  in  organic  connexion  with 
God,  the  things  of  time  with  those  of  eternity,  the  conditions  of  man's 
present  life  with  the  divine  plan. 

But  secondly,  this  internal  complexity  and  struggle  is  deepened  by 
struggles  and  complexities  from  without.  For  Christianity  became 
the  central  stream  of  human  history.  To  it,  every  current  of 
human  thinking,  of  human  passion,  of  human  achievement,  every 
scientific  tradition,  every  type  of  religion  and  of  religious  aspira 
tion,  became  tributary,  bringing  clear  or  troubled  waters,  which 
partly  were  received  and  assimilated,  partly  were  hurried  forward 
in  rival  and  contending  currents.  Virtually  all  the  types,  and 
all  the  divisions,  of  man's  science,  of  his  philosophy,  of  his  greater 
religion,  entered  and  exerted  their  influence;  so  that  he  who  would 
trace  the  development  within  Christendom  of  the  conception  of  God 
and  the  conception  of  God's  relation  to  nature  and  man,  would  have  to 
make  himself  acquainted  in  the  end  with  nothing  less  than  the  whole 
scientific  and  religious  history  of  the  human  race. 

In  the  pages  that  remain,  not  even  a  beginning  can  be  made  at  the 
telling  of  that  great  history.1  But  the  impression  which  it  is  the 
business  of  this  book  to  convey — an  impression  of  the  two  funda 
mental  tendencies  in  the  endeavour  of  the  soul  to  move  intellectually 
and  practically  toward  reality — calls  for  at  least  some  indication  of  the 
complexity  of  the  development  now  in  question ;  calls  for  at  least  some 
glimpse  of  the  variety  of  interests  and  insights  operative  in  it,  of  the 
crossing,  the  conflicting,  the  involution,  of  its  intellectual  and 
emotional  and  moral  factors. 

i  A  condensed  outline,  firmly  and  clearly  drawn,  of  the  more  positive  side  of  it,  is 
given  by  Principal  Fairbairn  in  Book  I.  of  his  Place  of  Christ  in  Modern  Theology. 

266 


THE    COMPLETING    OF    IDEALISM 

In  attempting  to  give  such  an  indication,  it  is  scarcely  possible  to 
touch  the  modern  world.  On  the  practical  side,  the  story  is  too  hope 
lessly  vast;  and  the  issues  are  not  yet  clear.  On  the  side  of  thought 
the  history  is  easier  to  follow;  and  there  are  two  specially  striking 
examples  of  the  direct  entanglement  and  conflict  of  the  two  tendencies 
— Spinoza,  and  Kant.  But  with  Spinoza  we  have  already  attempted  to 
deal.  While  that  veiled  conflict  of  the  abstract  and  the  concrete 
movement  of  thought,  which  ran  through  the  whole  structure  of 
Kant's  critical  philosophy,  has  been  laid  bare  for  us  by  the  Master  of 
Balliol  in  an  exposition  which  is  one  of  the  masterworks  of  English 
philosophical  literature.  But  for  the  present  purpose  the  mediaeval 
world  is  almost  more  instructive  than  our  own;  because  in  it  life  and 
thought  went  more  closely  hand  in  hand.  Turning  to  it,  we  are  to 
attempt  to  deal  with  two  single  points  which  illustrate  the  wealth  and 
complexity  of  the  forces  at  work.  The  one  is  Erigena's  view  of  the 
Division  of  Nature;  it  goes  beyond  the  story  of  the  inner  develop 
ment  of  Idealism,  and  takes  us  back  to  that  ultimate  antithesis  with 
which  we  were  concerned  on  earlier  pages;  for  it  shows  the  Idealism 
implicit  in  Christianity  almost  overborne  by  Neo-Platonic  Mysticism. 
The  other  is  an  aspect  of  Aquinas'  conception  of  the  relation  of  the 
world  to  God.  It  shows  us  that  implicit  Idealism  struggling  toward 
a  thorough  expression  of  itself,  but  crossed  just  at  the  culmination  by 
a  dualism  very  similar  in  motive  to  that  of  Plato  and  Aristotle. 


267 


ERIGENA  :    THE  DIVISION  OP  NATURE 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE. 

MEN  more  different  than  Erigena  and  Spinoza  it  would  be  hard 
to  imagine ;  or  philosophies  more  different  in  atmosphere  and  outward 
appearance  than  Spinoza's  with  its  severity  of  science,  and  Erigena's 
with  its  radiance  of  mystic  passion.  Yet  in  the  inner  logic  of  the  two 
philosophies  there  is  a  similarity:  each  in  its  own  way  shows  us  the 
affirmative  method  and  the  negative  dwelling  together  in  a  single 
mind.  This  was  due  in  part  to  the  very  nature  of  their  endeavour. 
As  men  of  philosophy  and  of  religion,  they  strove  to  see  the  world 
as  One;  strove  to  pass  from  present  appearances  to  eternal  reality. 
But,  as  we  so  often  have  seen,1  there  are  in  such  a  movement  of  thought 
two  possibilities.  We  may  see  that  the  present  appearances  must 
somehow  be  in  organic  connexion  with  eternal  reality;  for  else  the 
world  is  hopelessly  rent  in  twain,  and  the  very  unity  that  we  set  out 
to  find  is  lost.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  we  may  be  so  overwhelmed  by 
the  difference^between  reality  in  its  oneness  and  perfection,  and  the 
appearances  in  their  dividedness  and  evil,  that  we  refuse  to  regard 
these  appearances  as  real  at  all ;  they  are  deceptions — shadows  of  the 
cave — coloured  veils  breaking  up  the  pure  light  of  the  One.  And 
between  the  two  possibilities,  thus  inherent  in  the  very  nature  of  their 
task,  both  Erigena  and  Spinoza  divided  their  hearts.  But  the  form 
which  this  division  of  mind  assumed  was  determined  for  each  by  his 
own  special  circumstances ;  in  each  case  there  was  a  preceding  history 
leading  to  the  presence  and  combination  of  the  two  tendencies  in  one 
outlook  upon  the  world.  For  Spinoza  there  stood  on  the  one  side  the 
modern  attempt  to  apprehend  reality  by  the  use  of  the  category  of 
Substance — the  Cartesian  tradition,  whose  last  prophet  is  shut  up  to 
the  belief  that  reality  is  One  Substance,  and  all  manifoldness  an 
illusion.  On  the  other  stood  the  newly-developed  physical  science, 
whose  temper  and  point  of  view  formed  part  of  Spinoza's  very  soul. 

i  Cf.  supra,  pp.  7-11 ;  p.  83  note ;  p.  117  .s-ey. ;  p.  216  sty/. 
271 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

With  Erigena,  the  diverse  traditions  that  made  up  his  intellectual 
inheritance  lay  closer  to  historical  religion.  First,  there  was  the  early 
history  of  Christian  theology :  the  Apologists  had  wrought  out  a  large- 
hearted  theory  of  divine  revelation,  of  God's  manifestation  of  Himself 
in  general  and  special  forms  to  all  the  world;  and  then  Fathers  and 
Councils  had  formulated  the  doctrine  of  the  Trinity.  But  along  with 
this  Christian  theology  and  strangely  interwoven  with  it,  there  came 
another  type  of  thought :  the  philosophy  which  called  itself  by  Plato's 
name,  but  really  was  the  summing  up  and  the  testament  of  the  ancient 
civilisation  that  had  gone  down  to  death,  and  in  dying  had  turned  its 
eyes  away  from  the  world  to  an  absolutely  transcendent  God. 

Such  a  combination  of  Christianity  and  Neo-Platonism  might  have 
seemed  beyond  possibility.  For  whether  viewed  as  theologies,  seeking 
to  pass  from  the  manifoldness  of  the  world  to  an  apprehension  of  its 
eternal  unity,  or  as  religions  seeking  the  way  of  life  by  which  man 
becomes  at  one  with  that  supreme  principle,  the  two  represent  the 
greatest  possible  opposition  of  method  and  tendency.  Extreme 
opposites  they  were,  too,  by  historical  position.  Neo-Platonism  was  at 
once  the  ultimate  vision  and  the  dying  voice  of  the  ancient  world; 
Christianity  was  the  vital  life  of  the  new.  And  this  opposition  of 
nature  had  manifested  itself  in  open  hostility  of  action?  Neo-Platon 
ism,  in  the  stress  of  its  conflict,  had  made  alliance  with  the  cult  of  the 
ancient  gods.  Nothing  could  better  have  marked  the  Neo-Platonist's 
sense  of  the  irreconcilableness  of  his  theology  with  the  Christian ;  nor, 
in  the  eyes  of  the  Catholic  theologian,  could  more  thoroughly  have 
displayed  Neo-Platonism  as  damned  beyond  all  hope. 

But  though  the  old  world  was  gone,  and  relapse  into  any  of  its 
faiths  or  worships  was  regarded  as  the  sin  of  sins,  yet  its  mind  could 
not  die.  The  Mysticism,  with  which  in  its  old  age  it  had  sought  to  rise 
above  itself,  neither  did  nor  could  pass  out  of  the  minds  of  men.  In 
part  Christianity  overcame  it ;  but  in  part  it  infused  itself  into  Chris 
tianity.  And  so  strong  is  the  impulse  of  the  human  mind  to  bring  to 
unity  all  the  insights  and  beliefs  that  have  place  in  it,  that  the  com 
bination  even  of  these  opposites  was  soon  attempted.  No  sooner  had 
the  great  world-conflict  been  fought  and  settled,  no  sooner  had  history, 
in  a  Justinian,  given  its  decisive  answer  to  the  endeavour  of  Julian, 

272 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

than  the  Areopagite  sought  to  give  to  a  modified  Neo-Platonism  a 
standing  within  the  church.  And  the  Areopagite  did  not  stand  alone ; 
he  had  many  teachers  and  compeers — Monophysite  monks,  for  instance, 
such  as  the  real  Stephen  bar  Sudaili  and  the  phantom  Heirotheus. 
But  the  passion  of  the  conflict  was  still  deep  enough  to  sharpen  the 
critical  sense  against  books  "  unknown  to  Cyril  and  Athanasius."  This 
ghost  of  Neo-Platonism,  in  its  Christian  dress,  could  but  wander 
forward  through  the  years,  here  and  there  (as  in  the  case  of  Maximus 
the  Confessor)  speaking  home  to  an  elect  heart,  but  by  the  great  body 
of  the  orthodox  misunderstood,  suspected,  or  even  condemned. 

None  the  less,  the  combination  was  to  take  place.  When  Julian 
and  Justinian  and  the  Areopagite  all  were  gone,  and  the  northern  races 
were  seated  beyond  possibility  of  overthrow  in  the  West — while  Mercia 
still  was  disputing  with  her  rivals  the  supremacy  of  England,  and 
there  were  yet  nearly  forty  years  to  the  birth  of  Alfred  the  West-Saxon 
— there  was  growing  up,  probably  in  some  corner  of  Ireland  with  a 
cloister  school,  the  man  who  was  to  stand  at  the  beginning  of  the 
greater  labours  of  mediaeval  theology.  But  he  was  not  to  stand  there 
merely  as  a  churchman  systematising  canonic  doctrine.  He  received 
into  himself  both  the  traditions  now  in  question — the  Christian 
theology  of  the  Trinity  and  the  Incarnation,  and  the  Neo-Platonism 
contained  in  the  mystical  theology  of  Dionysius.  These  he  welded  into 
a  system  which  sounds  the  note  and  contains  the  motives  of  each  of 
the  two  great  sides  of  mediseval  thought — the  mystic  side  and  the 
scholastic ;  but  which  does  much  more.  For  Erigena  was,  in  the  strict 
sense  of  the  word,  a  secular  figure,  a  man  who  belongs  to  the  ages ;  in 
him  the  great  histories  that  had  gone  before  him  found  a  voice  again ; 
while  with  his  endeavour  to  see  the  whole  process  of  the  world  as  a 
spiritual  process,  he  from  his  ninth  century  may  speak,  as  Noack 
points  out,1  to  the  men  of  the  nineteenth  with  their  Hegel.  Nature 
and  history  seem  to  have  worked  together  in  setting  him  in  his  fateful 
place.  He  was  a  Christian ;  by  training,  a  theologian  in  the  succession 
of  Christian  theologians.  But  by  special  kinship  of  nature  he  was 
fitted  to  receive,  and,  so  far  as  was  possible  to  a  man  who  in  his  subtle 
and  unusual  genius  must  have  stood  almost  alone,  to  introduce  as  a 

i  In  the  Vorwort  to  his  German  translation  of  the  De  Divisione  Naturae. 
19  273 


EBIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

factor  in  the  life  of  the  West,  that  older  theology  to  which  God  is  all 
in  all  and  the  world  an  emanation  from  which  the  wise  man  will  seek 
to  return  into  God  Himself. 

Eor  the  mind  of  Erigena  was  dominated  by  that  which  was  central 
to  the  logic  of  Neo-Platonism,  and  which  in  some  form  is  central  to 
all  philosophy — the  instinct  for  unity.  And  by  that  instinct  in  both 
its  forms.  As  a  philosophic  or  scientific  instinct,  it  constrained  him 
to  view  the  world,  and  all  the  history  and  process  of  the  world,  as 
one — as  one  reality,  issuing  from  one  source,  and  in  all  its  steps  and 
stages  remaining  one.  While  as  a  religious  passion,  the  passion  for 
unity  with  God,  it  joined  itself  with  the  philosophic  instinct  to 
strengthen  the  demand  that,  as  all  things  proceed  from  God,  all  things 
must  in  the  end  return  to  God. 

But  the  instinct  for  unity  has  two  ways  of  fulfilling  itself.  First 
,it  may  conceive  the  unity  of  all  existence  as  a  unity  which  mediates 
itself  through  diversity: — the  unity  which  a  system,  for  instance,  has 
by  reason  of  its  highest  principle,  or  which  a  process  has  by  reason  of 
the  purpose  that  is  realised  in  it.  Or,  secondly,  it  may  conceive  the 
unity  of  the  real  as  the  solid,  undifferentiated  unity  which  rejects  from 
itself  all  manifoldness,  all  diversities,  all  distinctions.  Of  the  two 
conceptions,  the  latter  is  the  easier  to  form;  particularly  in  early 
thought.  Hence  the  man  who  is  dominated  by  precisely  the  central 
impulse  of  all  science  and  of  all  philosophy,  often  conceives  the  unity 
that  he  seeks  as  of  the  latter  type.  And  from  this,  for  the  man  of 
intellectual  clearness  and  speculative  courage,  the  consequences  follow 
at  once.  The  One  is,  and  nothing  else  is.  Then  what  is  the  manifold 
world  of  our  experience?  It  is  illusion.  And  if  the  inquirer  is  a 
religious  man,  he  has  to  go  a  step  farther.  The  welfare  of  the  soul 
lies  with  reality.  The  duty  of  a  true  man,  therefore,  is  to  lift  himself 
out  of  the  illusion  in  which  ordinary  human  life  is  spent.  He  must 
seek  a  new  type  of  experience,  a  new  form  of  consciousness,  in  which 
he  enters  into  union  with  reality ;  in  which  he  lays  aside  the  finitude 
and  manifoldness  of  human  individuality,  and  without  distinction  or 
division  of  essence  becomes  one  with  God. 

The  key  to  Erigena's  position  is  that  he  cannot  enter  clearly  into 
the  former  of  these  two  ways  of  philosophy,  nor  yet  commit  himself 

274 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

unreservedly  to  the  latter.  Cannot  enter  clearly  into  the  former :  for 
he  does  not  possess,  in  clear  mastery,  those  "  categories  of  organic 
unity  "  which  enable  human  thought  to  retain  all  the  manif oldness  of 
the  given  world,  and  yet  view  that  wTorld  as  having  the  genuine  unity 
of  a  system  or  process  in  which  a  single  principle  is  manifesting  itself, 
a  single  purpose  being  realised.  Nor  can  he  commit  himself 
unreservedly  to  the  latter.  For  his  mind  was  not  only  subtle  and  acute. 
It  was  comprehensive  also,  delighting  to  traverse  all  the  ranges  of 
existence.  And  his  spirit  seems  to  have  been  affectionate;  seems  to 
have  cast  out  many  tendrils  that  clung  about  the  things  and  persons 
of  the  manifold  world;  as  frequently  his  parabolae  with  their  keen  eye 
for  the  face  of  nature,  show,  or  the  tender  dedication  subinde  dilectis- 
simo  tibi;  frater  in  Christo  Wulfade,  et  in  studiis  sapientiae  coopera- 
tori,  at  the  close  of  the  De  Divisione  Naturae.  But  behind  all  such 
personal  reasons  stands  the  greater  historical  one — his  inheritance  of 
Christianity  and  of  Christian  theology.  His  vision  of  the  Lord  Christ 
taking  upon  Him  the  form  of  our  mortal  life,  forbade  him  to  dismiss 
the  world  of  our  present  struggle  as  unreality  and  illusion. 

So  that  Erigena's  work  was  done  under  almost  the  greatest  strain 
that  can  come  upon  a  man  in  the  courts  of  philosophy.  By  imperious 
necessities  of  thought  within,  by  great  histories  without,  he  was  com 
pelled  to  be  faithful  both  to  the  Many  and  to  the  One;  and  at  the 
same  time  he  was  not  clearly  master  of  those  categories  which  would 
have  enabled  him  not  merely  to  keep  both  the  Many  and  the  One,  but 
to  see  each  as  necessary  to  the  other.  Hence  he  was  in  a  continual 
struggle  to  keep  faithful  to  his  belief  in  the  unity  of  existence,  and  at 
the  same  time  to  do  justice  to  the  diverse  facts  of  that  manifold  world 
which  was  given  to  his  singularly  open-eyed  and  sensitive  spirit.  And 
what  he  built  up  under  the  pressure  of  that  struggle  was  a  system  that 
has  virtually  all  the  great  conceptions  and  tendencies  and  traditions 
of  Alexandrian  and  mediaeval  thought  woven  into  it.  But  Erigena  did 
this  as  no  mere  eclectic,  piecing  together  into  an  unstable  structure 
materials  afforded  by  the  histories  that  he  inherited.  He  was  in 
himself  a  great  speculative  genius.  And  his  spirit  is  in  the  system 
that  he  constructed.  In  all  that  age  of  great  philosophies  and 
theologies  which  reaches  from  Augustine  to  Cusanus,  it  has  no  equal 

275 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

for  its  swift  and  free  ascent  of  the  secular  consciousness  to  its  home  in 
God,  or  for  the  unfailing  speculative  passion  with  which  it  carries 
through  the  idea  of  the  whole  world  as  a  procession  from 
God.  And  it  is  the  more  remarkable  as  having  taken  form  in  the 
ninth  century — as  if,  through  grey  and  cloudy  twilight  of  earliest 
morning  there  should  break,  for  one  fugitive  moment  and  with  the 
many-coloured  radiance  that  speaks  of  evening  rather  than  of  morning, 
the  flame  of  day. 

The  dialogue  in  which  Erigena  presents  this  system  is  long,  com 
plicated,  self -involved.  Continually  the  argument  returns  upon  itself ; 
yet  not  with  the  mere  vexatious  iteration  of  some  of  the  later  School 
men,  but  with  an  emphasis  that  always  is  new  and  with  a  "  subtle 
flame "  of  speculation  that  maintains  itself  to  the  end.  To  this 
dialogue — the  five  books  De  Divisione  Naturae — we  must  now  turn, 
and  attempt  to  follow  in  some  systematic  way  the  essential  movement 
of  its  thought.1 

First,  in  general  terms,  how  did  Erigena  meet  the  situation  just 
described?  He  keeps  both  sides,  we  must  answer;  and  does  this  by 
means  of  an  expedient  that  came  to  him  from  an  earlier  history. 

First,  he  keeps  the  unity.  To  say  this,  indeed,  is  only  to  say  that 
he  is  Erigena  and  a  philosopher.  Always  he  is  asserting  it,  or  taking 
it  for  granted,  or  labouring  to  reduce  to  it  the  stubborn  opposites  of 
the  world.  The  very  title  of  his  book,  which  seems  to  indicate  multi 
plicity,  really  points  toward  unity.  The  object  of  his  thinking,  the 
object  of  philosophy  and  theology,  he  calls  Nature.  But  by  Nature 
Tie  means  TO  nav,  the  totality  of  being  viewed  as  one;  and  by  the 
Forms  into  which  Nature  is  divided  he  means  the  aspects  which  that 
<one  reality  has  somehow  come  to  present.  But  secondly,  as  we  shall 

i  The  references  are  to  the  edition  of  Floss  (Migne,  vol.  122  of  the  Latin  Patrology).— 
"It  is  a  question  whether  Erigena,  with  his  passion  for  the  point  of  view  of  eternity,  did 
•not  (in  speaking  of  the  Word)  frequently  write  ingenitus  where  Floss  reads  unigenitus. 

Except  at  one  or  two  points  (where  Erigena,  in  his  scorn  for  the  human  body  as  con 
trasted  with  the  angelic,  is  driven  beyond  his  usual  fine  sensitiveness  and  allows  the 
language  with  which  he  condemns  the  brute  in  man,  itse'f  to  take  on  a  touch'of  brutality), 
J  have  made  the  translations  very  literal.  This  ha^  been  done  in  the  hope  of  conveying  a 
more  accurate  impression  of  the  man  himself  in  his  ninth  century  thought.  But  in  one 
way  it  is  scarcely  fair  to  him ;  the  depth  and  acuteness  of  his  mind  would  be  better  shown 
if  his  thoughts  were  turned  into  the  present-day  language  of  philosophy. 

276 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

see  more  fully  in  dealing  with  the  second  and  third  Forms  of  Nature, 
he  also  keeps  the  manifold;  though  no  man  need  imagine  that  the 
manifold  which  a  mediaeval  theologian,  and  a  disciple  of  the  Areopa- 
gite  at  that,  leaves  standing,  is  quite  the  same  as  the  manifold  of 
ordinary  experience. 

But,  retaining  thus  a  manifoldness  within  reality,  has  he  not 
shattered  his  own  fundamental  doctrine  of  the  unity  of  Nature  ?  The 
answer  is,  as  indicated  a  moment  ago,  that  he  escapes  the  difficulty 
altogether,  by  bringing  up  a  great  distinction  from  that  inheritance  of 
theological  tradition  which  was  his  intellectual  field  and  home.  This 
is  the  distinction  between  that  which  is  and  that  which  is  not;  and 
the  consequent  distinction  between  the  methods  of  apprehending  these 
two  kinds  of  reality.  The  opening  sentences  of  the  De  Divisione 
Naturae,  in  which  Erigena  chooses  for  the  totality  of  things  the  great 
word  Nature,  show  Nature  as  divided  into  the  things  that  are  and  the 
things  that  are  not: 

Master. — Often — as  I  ponder,  with  such  diligence  of  inquiry  as  my  powers 
admit,  upon  the  fact  that  the  first  and  highest  division  of  all  things  which 
can  either  be  perceived  by  mind  or  transcend  its  reach,  is  into  those  that 
are  and  those  that  are  not — there  presents  itself  to  me,  as  the  general  name 
of  all  these,  the  term  which  in  Greek  is  tyvoig-,  but  in  Latin  Natura.  Or  do 
you  view  the  matter  otherwise  ? 

Scholar. — Nay,  I  agree  ;  for  I,  too,  find  it  thus,  when  I  enter  upon  the  path 
of  rational  investigation. 

Master. — Nature,  then,  as  we  have  said,  is  the  general  name  for  all  things 
which  are  and  which  are  not. 

That  which  is  is  the  reality  able  to  present  itself  in  ordinary  human 
experience ;  the  reality  apprehensible  by  human  reason,  and  declared, 
therefore,  by  that  reason  to  have  existence.  But  there  is  a  reality 
which  stands  high  above  all  the  categories  of  reason,  and  of  which, 
therefore,  reason  can  only  say  that  it  is  not.  This  reality  which  is 
beyond  the  grasp  of  mind  and  can,  therefore,  in  all  thinking  and 
speaking,  be  referred  to  only  in  negative  terms  of  which  the  is  not  is 
the  summing  up,  is  the  true  and  genuine  reality.  And  with  it,  though 
human  thought  and  speech  can  find  no  name  for  it  except  Nothing 

277 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

and  no  description  of  it  except  that  it  is  not,  yet  a  union  of  the  soul 
is  possible ;  a  union  with  which  Erigena  deals  at  length,  but  which  we 
cannot  consider  at  this  point.  Corresponding  to  this  distinction  within 
Nature  is  a  distinction  in  theological  method.  There  is,  first,  affirma 
tive  theology,  which  of  the  divine  essence  predicates  what  is;  not 
meaning,  indeed,  that  the  divine  essence  is  anything  of  that  which 
is,  but  that  all  qualities  and  existences  which  have  their  source  in  it 
can  be  predicated  of  it.  While  negative  theology  denies  that  the  divine 
essence  falls  in  the  province  of  that  which  is;  i.e.,  of  that  which  can 
be  thought  or  spoken.1  You  can  say,  for  instance,  that  God  is  truth, 
inasmuch  as  He  is  the  creator  and  original  cause  of  that  truth  in 
which  all  things  that  are  true  participate.  But,  on  the  negative 
method,  you  deny  that  God  is  truth,  because  He  is  more  than  truth 
and  is  exalted  above  everything  that  can  be  thought  or  said,  above 
everything  of  which  it  can  at  all  be  said  that  it  is.2  And  of  these  two 
methods  or  procedures  of  theology,  the  preference  must  be  given  to 
the  negative.  For  what  the  affirmative  procedure  does,  is,  as  a  working 
compromise,  to  effect  a  sort  of  transfer:  it  carries  the  methods  of 
human  thinking  into  a  realm  where  properly  they  have  no  place. 
Categories  like  Essence,  Wisdom,  Truth,  it  applies  where  categories  are 
not  applicable.  In  strict  propriety,  it  is  only  the  via  negativa  that  can 
be  adopted  in  investigating  the  exalted  and  incomprehensible  nature  of 
God.  If  men  must  have  a  name  for  that  nature,  let  them  use  the  word 
that  expresses  the  inability  of  thought  to  conceive  it  and  of  speech  to 
utter  it — the  word  Nihil.  For  God,  being  exalted  above  all  that  can 
be  thought  or  uttered,  can  properly  be  affirmed  only  by  the  denial  of 

1  I.  13,  14.    The  argument  of  chapter  14  is  one  that  has  taken  a  great  place  in  the 
history  of  theologia  negativa.    God  is  viewed  as  coincidentia  oppositorum.    Hence  you 
must  not  attribute  one  side  of  an  opposition  or   antithesis   to  God  without  the  other. 
But  human  thought— so  Erigena  takes  for  granted,  whatever  deeper  view  may  be  implicit 
in  him— has  no  conceptions  which  take  up  into  unity  both  sides  of  these  oppositions. 
Hence  human  thought  is  precluded  from  attributing  qualities  to  God  at  all,  and  has  to 
regard  Him  as  altogether  beyond  the  categories.     It  will  be  noted,  that  with  these  opposi 
tions,  e.g.,  Essence  and  Nothingness,  Eternity  and  Time,  Light  and  Darkness,  Erigena 
does  not  regard  the  latter  as  merely  a  denial  of  the  former,  but  views  both  as  positive. 
Then  since  God  is  the  source  of  both,  affirmative  theology  must  predicate  both  of  Him ; 
which  can  only  mean  that  He  is  above  both,  and  that  therefore  (as  is  noted  in  the  text)  the 
true  procedure  for  theology  is  the  negative  procedure. 

2  IV.  5. 

278 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUEE 

all  that  is;  and  is  better  known  by  non-knowledge.1  Thus,  then,  the 
negative  method  avails  us  more  than  the  affirmative,  in  our  inevitable 
attempt  to  characterise  the  ineffable  essence  of  God.  For  affirmative 
theology  is  a  carrying  over  of  qualities  or  predicates  from  the  creatures 
to  the  Creator ;  but  the  denials  of  negative  theology,  moving  far  above 
every  creature,  are  valid  of  the  Creator  in  and  for  Himself.2  Hence 
it  is  that  Erigena  adopts  the  exhortation  of  the  Areopagite  to 
Timotheus  his  friend :  "  If  thou  art  strong  for  journeying  in  the 
realm  of  mystic  contemplation,  forsake  the  senses  and  the  operations 
of  the  intellect,  and  both  the  things  of  sense  and  the  things  that  are 
invisible,  and  all  that  is  and  is  not,  and  so  far  as  in  thee  lieth  be 
restored  in  non-knowledge  to  the  unity  of  that  which  is  above  all 
essence  and  all  science.  For  thus,  in  the  immeasurable  and  uncondi 
tional  passing  of  the  soul  beyond  thyself  and  all  things,  forsaking  all 
things,  and  from  all  things  being  set  free,  shalt  thou  ascend  to  the 
superessential  ray  of  the  divine  darkness." 

This  division  of  Nature  into  that  which  is  and  that  which  is  not, 
with  the  corresponding  distinction  between  the  methods  of  theology,  is 
the  expedient  which  sets  Erigena  free  from  his  initial  and  funda 
mental  difficulty.  First,  it  leaves  him  free  to  assert  the  very  highest 
doctrine  of  unity;  a  doctrine  of  unity  which  sets  him  at  the  side  of 
Vedantist  and  Neo-Platonist.  But  secondly,  it  also  leaves  him  free  to 
give  a  place  within  reality  to  the  manifold — the  manifold  of  our 
experience,  together  with  that  higher  system  of  forms  and  principles, 
of  persons  and  energies,  requisite  for  the  explanation  of  our  experi 
ence.  And  this  simultaneous  honouring  of  the  two  great  and  appar 
ently  antithetic  necessities — the  necessity  for  unity,  asserted  imperi 
ously  by  the  philosophic  and  theological  intellect;  and  the  necessity 
of  recognising  the  actual  manifold  of  our  experience — can  take  place 
without  fear  of  rational  attack.  For  Nature  as  one  (i.e.,  God  as 
original  source)  is  above  all  grasp  of  reason.  If  it  be  objected:  Does 

1  III.  20  and  22.    Erigena  feels  so  keenly  that  knowledge  conditions  and  limits  its 
object,  that  he  is  not  content  with  denying  that  human  reason  can  know  God.    He  even 
constructs,  under  certain  modifications,  a  doctrine  that  God  cannot  know  Himself  (II.  28). 
But  in  estimating  the  real  significance  of  such  a  view,  we  must  remember  that  for 
Krigena  knowledge  is  defined  by  the  ten  Aristotelian  categories. 

2  IV.  5, 

279 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

not  your  retention  of  the  manifold  contradict  your  doctrine  of  unity? 
the  answer  is :  You  cannot  say  that,  for  reason  cannot  enter  here ;  the 
nature  of  the  One  is  riot  to  be  limited  by  the  application  to  it  of  the 
categories.1 

Thus  a  "  Division  " — really  not  so  much  "  of  Nature,"  as  of  the 
aspects  which  Nature  presents  to  minds  like  ours2 — is  effected.  There 
is,  first,  Nature  as  One.  It  is  above  the  categories ;  we  cannot  ration 
ally  comprehend  it,  though  we  must  affirm  its  unity.  There  is, 
secondly,  Nature  as  Manifold.  This  is  the  field  wherein  reason  can 
profitably  employ  itself;  and  Erigena — as  if  rejoicing  that  his  funda 
mental  Mysticism  is  not  after  all  to  call  him  away  from  the  courts  of 
science  to  mystic  quietude — flings  himself  upon  it  with  all  the  powers 
of  his  subtle  and  eager  mind  and  all  the  resources  of  his  intellectual 
inheritance.  As  he  considers  it,  he  finds  within  it  a  great  distinction. 
There  are,  first,  the  universals — eternal  and  energetic  types;  what 
Plato  called  Ideas,  but  Erigena  calls  primordial  causes.  Secondly, 
there  are  the  effects  of  these  causes,  effects  of  which  some  at  least  are 
temporal  and  visible. 

But  even  this  is  not  the  end.  The  instinct  for  unity  still  has  a 
work  to  do,  and  here  it  is  especially  supported  by  the  religious  instinct. 
If  it  is  a  demand  of  reason  that  there  should  be  a  unitary  source  of  all 
things,  it  is  a  demand  both  of  reason  and  of  religion  that  there  should 
be  a  unitary  end  of  all  things.  So  that  the  final  Form  of  Nature  is 
that  in  which  there  is  no  more  procession — no  more  forth-going — of 
creatures  in  classes  and  kinds,  but  all  things,  in  quiet,  rest  in  God  as 
an  undivided  and  unchangeable  One.3 

Thus  the  "Division  of  Nature"  comes  at  last  to  be  fourfold. 
First,  there  is  Nature  as  One — Nature  as  creating,  but  not  created, 

1  It  is  interesting  to  compare  the  somewhat  similar  situation  in  Kant.    Moral  reason 
asserts  a  categorical  imperative.    And  that  assertion,  so  Kant  thinks,  the  scientific  reason 
cannot  challenge,  because  scientific  reason  cannot  enter  into  the  realm  of  noumena. 

2  Cf.  infra,  pp.  304-307  and  314-316  (especially  315).— At  the  beginning  of  the  third  Book, 
the  second  Form  of  Nature  is  referred  to  as  "  the  second  way  of  viewing  universal  Nature, 
and,  so  to  speak,  its  form  or  appearance."— In  Spinoza,  on  the  interpretation  of  those  who 
in  dealing  with  the  definition  of  "Attribute"  (Eth.  I.  def.  IV.)  emphasise  the  tanguam, 
there  is  a  similar  situation,  arising  out  of  similar  logical  motives. 

3  II.  2. 

280 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

God  as  the  original  source  of  all  things;  secondly,  the  aboriginal 
causes — Nature  as  created  and  creating ;  thirdly,  the  effects  of  these — 
Nature  as  created,  but  not  creating;  fourthly,  Nature  as  One  again, 
when  all  process  or  emanation  from  the  original  One  has  returned  to 
its  source,  and  God  is  all  in  all. 

To  the  consideration  of  these  four  Forms  of  Nature,  the  De 
Divisione  Naturae  is  given.  Of  the  first,  as  it  is  in  itself,  there  is,  of 
course,  nothing  to  be  said,  except  in  the  way  of  amplifying  the  negative 
position  already  indicated.  This  Erigena  specially  does  in  the  first 
Book,  a  great  part  of  which  is  occupied  by  an  extended  proof  of  the 
inapplicability  of  the  ten  Aristotelian  categories  to  God.  The  Book 
concludes  by  insisting  once  more  upon  the  greater  truth  of  the  negative 
theology.  "  And  this  is  the  Confession,  prudent  and  catholic  and  for 
our  salvation,  which  we  are  to  make  concerning  God: — that  we  may 
first,  in  the  affirmative  way,  using  names  or  words,  predicate  all  things 
of  Him,  not  properly,  but  by  a  certain  transfer;  but  that  all  these 
may  again  with  full  propriety  be  denied  of  Him  according  to  the 
negative  way.  For  it  is  more  correct  to  deny,  than  to  affirm,  that  God 
is  anything  of  that  which  is  predicated  of  Him."1  "  ...  Of 
God  nothing  can  properly  be  predicated,  because  He  is  above  every 
thought,  above  every  characterisation  in  form  of  sense  or  intelligence ; 
better  is  He  known  through  non-knowledge ;  His  absence  of  knowledge 
is  the  true  wisdom ;  more  truly  and  more  credibly  is  He  denied  in  all 
than  affirmed.  For  whatsoever  thou  deniest  of  Him  thou  deniest 
truly ;  but  in  no  wise  does  that  which  our  reason  establishes  about  Him 
stand  fast  in  reality.  If  trjiou  provest  (appro!) averis,  imaginest  thyself 
to  have  proven)  that  He  is  this  or  that,  thou  shalt  stand  in  the  end 
convicted  of  falsehood,  because  He  is  nothing  of  all  those  things  which 
are,  or  which  can  be  said  or  thought.  If,  however,  thou  declarest  that 
He  is  neither  this,  nor  that,  nor  any  definite  thing  (nee  hoc,  nee  illud, 
nee  ullum),  then  thy  truthfulness  shall  be  made  manifest  because  He 
is  nothing  of  all  those  things  which  are  and  which  are  not.  To  him  no 
man  can  draw  near,  unless  first,  making  strong  the  path  of  the  soul,  he 

i  I.  76.— Erigena   likes   to   call   affirmative   theology  cataphatic,  negative   theology 
apophatic. 

281 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

leaves  behind  him  all  the  senses,  and  the  activities  of  the  understand 
ing,  and  all  the  things  of  sense,  together  with  the  whole  of  that  which  is 
and  which  is  not,  and  so  far  as  in  him  lies  is  restored  in  non-knowledge 
to  unity  with  Him  who  is  far  above  every  essence  and  all  thought; 
for  whom  neither  ^reason  nor  thinking  is  suitable,  nor  can  He  be 
uttered  or  understood,  nor  is  there  for  Him  name  or  word."1 

And  yet  something  positive  must  be  said  about  the  first  Form  of 
Nature.  For  Erigena  is  simply  not  capable  of  affirming  a  One  above 
the  categories,  and  a  Many  subject  to  the  categories,  and  then  merely 
leaving  these  side  by  side,  with  the  statement  that  nothing  can  be  said 
affirmatively  of  the  One,  and  that  therefore  the  only  thing  for  us  to  do 
is  to  describe  the  Manifold  as  we  find  it.  So  that,  although  the  first 
Form  of  Nature  is  above  the  categories,  yet  Erigena  does  after  all 
make  it  an  object  of  positive  philosophical  investigation;  he  considers, 
namely,  its  outgoing  or  procession  into  the  lower  Forms,  and  so  gives 
us  a  view  of  the  universe  of  particular  beings,  as  unfolded  from  an 
original  unity. 

That  is  to  say,  Erigena  turns  to  affirmative  theology.  The  very 
next  sentence  after  the  passage  just  quoted,  goes  on :  "  But,  on  the 
other  hand,  as  we  have  often  said,  without  precisely  contradicting 
reason,  all  the  things  which  are,  from  the  highest  to  the  lowest,  can  be 
predicated  of  God,  in  the  way  of  a  certain  similarity,  or  dissimilarity, 
or  contrariety,  or  opposition,  since  all  the  things  which  may  be  predi 
cated  of  Him  have  their  source  in  Him."  Then  the  second  Book 
makes  a  formal  transition  to  the  theology  of  affirmation,  in  which,  in 
our  reflective  consideration  of  the  universe,  we  may  by  a  sort  of 
transfer  apply  the  terms  and  methods  of  our  human  science  to  God, 
"  since  everything  which  has  its  being  in  Him  and  from  Him,  may 
with  piety  and  reason  be  predicated  of  him."2  Later  in  the  second 
Book,  the  same  transition  is  again  indicated;  for  while  in  the  De 
Divisions  Naturae  there  is  an  orderly  plan  and  advance,  yet  the 
book  is  like  a  gleaming  web',  in  which  all  the  strands  are  present  at 
the  beginning  and  continually  are  reappearing.  So  that  after  dealing 
in  the  earlier  part  of  the  second  Book  with  the  procession  of  the 
primordial  causes  from  God,  and  with  the  nature  of  man, — drawing 

i  I.  66.  2  II.  i. 

282 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

his  doctrines  with  inimitable  exegesis  from  "  divinissimus  propheta, 
Moisen"1 — he  turns  back  to  the  inapplicability  of  the  categories  to 
God;  and  to  God's  non-knowledge  which  is  "  ineffable  understanding/' 
the  "  true  and  highest  wisdom  "  f  then  returns  to  the  doctrine  of  the 
Trinity  thus :  "  Let  us  now  turn  again  to  theology,  which  is  the  first 
and  chiefest  part  of  wisdom.  Rightly  is  it  called  so,  because  it  is 
concerned  either  solely  or  principally  with  the  contemplation  of  the 
divine  nature.  It  falls  into  two  parts,  an  affirmative  and  a  negative, 
which  in  Greek  are  called  uara<pariKi]  and  ano^acuuf.  In  the 
first  Book  we  dealt  with  negative  theology,  denying  upon  assured 
grounds  that  the  ten  categories — together  with  all  genera,  forms, 
numbers,  and  accidents — can  properly  be  predicated  of  God.  In  this 
present  Book  we  have  also  proceeded  according  to  the  negative  way,  as 
the  order  of  our  problem  demanded;  and  have  taken  up  the  position, 
that  God  in  His  essence  understands  nothing  of  all  that,  which  is  and 
is  not,  because  He  transcends  every  essence;  that  He  absolutely  does 
not  know  what  He  is  (since  He  is  in  no  wise  determined  or  condi 
tioned),  or  of  what  quantity  or  quality  He  is  (since  no  such  deter 
mination  attaches  to  Him  and  He  is  in  nothing  to  be  understood)  ; 
and  that  He  in  Himself  absolutely  cannot  be  comprehended  in  that 
which  is  and  that  which  is  not : — a  sort  of  non-knowledge  which  stands 
high  above  all  knowledge  and  understanding.  But  now  let  us  attempt 
to  gain  an  insight  into  the  other  part,  into  affirmative  theology,  under 
the  leadership  of  Him,  who  is  sought  and  seeks  to  be  sought;  who 
comes  to  meet  the  souls  that  seek  Him,  and  desires  to  be  found.  This 
part  of  theology  it  is  which,  with  regard  to  the  divine  nature,  considers 
what  may  with  a  certain  propriety  be  brought  forward,  and  be  under 
stood  by  reason  if  it  go  prudently."3 

We  have  already  noted  the  forms  or  stages  under  which  Erigena 
considers  the  procession  by  which  the  one  eternal  Nature  gives  rise  to 
a  manifold  reality.  The  first  stage  in  the  forth-going  process — what 
Erierena  calls  the  second  Form  of  Nature — contains  a  multitude  of 

O 

existences,  the  causae  primordiales.     These  are  perfect;    are    purely 

1  II.  15. 

2  II.  2S.—Ipsius  enim  ignorantia  incffabilis  cst  intelligentia.     .    .    .      Ipsa   itague 
ignorantia  summa  ac  vera  est  sapientia. 

3  H.  30. 

283 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

intelligible,  unmixed  with  space  or  time;  are  at  once  creative 
energies  and  the  archetypes  after  which  the  things  of  this  world  are 
found; — in  a  word,  are  Platonic  Ideas.  Yet  Erigena  is  never  weary 
of  insisting  that  this  second  Form  of  Nature  is  a  unity.  That  is  to 
say,  he  really  views  it  as  a  system — a  system  of  intelligible  forms,  a 
xoffj^os  vorjTOS.  Then  the  third  Form,  into  which  the  second 
proceeds,  contains  the  actual  things  and  beings  of  this  present  world. 
We  shall  best  understand  Erigena's  position  in  this — shall  best 
set  before  our  minds  both  the  difficulties  that  he  faced,  and  the 
solutions  that  he  found  for  them — if  we  turn  back  for  a  moment  to 
Neo-Platonism,  and  alongside  the  solutions  that  Plotinus  worked  out 
for  the  difficulties  which  beset  him,  place  the  solutions  that  Erigena 
worked  out  for  precisely  the  same  difficulties.  The  One  of  Plotinus, 
like  Erigena's  first  Form  of  Nature,  is  absolutely  a  unity;  it  rejects 
from  itself  all  diversity  and  manifoldness.  And  it  is  absolutely 
transcendent;  so  that  reason  can  attain  to  no  comprehension  of  it. 
Yet  the  manifold  world  of  our  experience  is  left  standing ;  and,  since 
dualism  is  intolerable,  that  absolutely  transcendent  principle  is 
necessarily  regarded  as  the  source  of  it.  But  then  arises  at  once  the 
problem :  How  can  the  One  remain  in  its  absolute  transcendence  and 
absolute  self-containedness,  and  yet  give  rise  to  this  present  world? 
The  steps  in  Plotinus'  attempt  to  solve  this  problem  we  have  already 
had  to  consider.1  First,  he  has  two  devices  for  enabling  him  to  regard 
the  One  as  giving  rise  to  something  beyond  itself,  and  yet  as  remaining 
in  its  absolute  unity.  One  of  these  devices  consists  in  metaphor;  the 
procession  of  some  further  reality  from  the  One  is  emanation,  which 
leaves  the  source  precisely  what  it  was  before — as  fragrance  does  the 
flower  from  which  it  comes,  or  light  the  flame,  or  cold  the  snow.  The 
other  is  that  most  ingenious  of  logical  devices,  the  conception  of  one- 
ended  relationship:  "It  (the  One)  is  by  no  means  that  of  which  it 
is  the  principle."  Thus  the  passage  is  made  from  the  One  to  that 
which,  in  Plotinus'  system,  corresponds  to  the  second  Form  of  Nature 
in  Erigena's;  to  the  rovs.  This  is  viewed  as  at  once  one  and  many. 
It  is  a  Hoafj.0*  vorjros,  a  place  of  intelligible  forms,  the  home  of  the 
Ideas  or  archetypes  after  which  the  things  of  the  visible  world  are 

i  Supra,  pp.  142-144. 
284 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

made;  i.e.,  at  this  point  Plotinus  weaves  into  his  system  the  Platonic 
theory  of  Ideas.  And  as  the  roCs  is  an  emanation  from  the  One,  so 
it  is  itself  the  source  of  a  farther  emanation,  and  thus  we  are  led  at 
last  to  our  present  world. 

But  such  a  view  involves  difficulties,  of  which  we  must  here  notice 
three.  (1)  There  is  the  difficulty  in  deriving  the  rous  from  the  One 
at  all.  (2)  There  is  a  difficulty  in  what  may  be  called  the  internal 
constitution  of  the  vovs.  As  an  emanation  from  the  One  it  also  is 
One;  but  toward  the  world — as  containing  the  Ideas  or  archetypes  of 
the  world — it  is  many.  But  the  two  sides  of  the  conception  are  not 
adequately  held  together.  The  rovs  is  a  one;  and  it  is  a  many;  but 
what  the  principle  or  energy  of  synthesis  is,  which  thus  enables  a  one 
to  be  at  the  same  time  a  many,  Plotinus  does  not  and  cannot  explain. 
(3)  The  difficulty  in  the  relation  of  the  One  to  the  rovs  recurs  in  the 
relation  of  the  rovs  to  the  world  below  it.  How  does  the  rovs  go 
beyond  itself  to  give  rise  to  the  manifold  world  of  our  sense-experi 
ence?  This  difficulty  is  almost  the  same  as  that  in  Plato's  earlier 
Idealism  with  regard  to  the  relation  of  the  Ideas  to  the  manifold 
things  of  sense. 

These  difficulties  are  all  in  a  sense  contained  in  the  first.  Any 
adequate  solution  of  it  would  almost  certainly  involve  the  solution  of 
the  others.  But  precisely  that  first  difficulty  it  is  which  is  absolutely 
hopeless.  When  God  or  reality  is  defined  in  the  Neo-Platonic  way  as 
absolutely  one,  absolutely  self-contained,  absolutely  transcendent, 
there  is  no  possibility  whatever  of  advancing  to  a  manifold  world. 
You  are  shut  up  to  the  position  of  the  Vedantist  and  of  Parmenides. 
There  simply  is  no  such  thing  as  a  manifold  world.  Belief  in  it  is  an 
illusion ;  and  a  wise  man's  business  is  to  free  himself  from  the  illusion. 

But,  as  we  have  seen,1  Plotinus  could  not  take  up  that  position.  He 
cannot  deny  the  existence  of  the  manifold  world,  and  therefore  is 
compelled  to  attempt  in  the  way  just  noticed  a  derivation  of  it  from 
the  One.  But  the  derivation  is  altogether  unsatisfactory.  The  meta 
phors  do  not  help  us;  metaphors  may  illustrate  arguments,  but  are 
not  themselves  arguments.  And  the  conception  of  a  one-ended 
relationship  must  be  rejected  as  contradicting  the  very  idea  of 

1  Supra,  p.  142. 
285 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

relationship.  What  really  lies  behind  these  devices  is  the  fact  that  in 
Plotinus  there  are  two  types  of  thinking:  the  mystic  thinking  to 
which  reality  is  an  absolutely  self-contained  One  admitting  no  multi 
plicity;  and  the  thinking  which  views  the  One  as  the  source  of  the 
manifold  world.  The  same  two  types  of  thinking  are  in  Spinoza ;  we 
have  already  had  to  study  the  way  in  which  he  makes  the  transition 
from  the  one  to  the  other — the  way  in  which  Spinoza  the  Mystic,  with 
his  One  Substance  that  can  have  no  determinations.,  passes  over  into 
Spinoza  the  Pantheist  to  whom  that  indeterminate  One  has  become  the 
self-determining  energy  of  an  orderly  and  systematic  world.1  One 
might  almost  say  that  the  chief  difference  between  the  two  is  that  in 
Plotinus  the  Mystic  predominates,  in  Spinoza  the  Pantheist.  And 
the  same  two  types  of  thinking  are  in  Erigena;  only  with  him  it  is 
hard  to  say  which  predominates.  In  fact,  he  is  completely  in  earnest 
with  both.  On  almost  every  page  can  be  found  the  ideas  which 
represent  the  two  sides :  the  idea  of  God — the  first  Form  of  Nature — 
as  absolutely  transcending  our  knowledge,  and  as  that  absolute  unity 
which  repels  all  diversity ;  and  the  idea  of  God  "  pouring  Himself 
forth,"  and  so  giving  rise  to  the  various  orders  of  existence  which 
make  up  the  universe.  And  he  does  not  seem  to  have  seen,  how  incom 
patible  these  types  of  thinking  are.  There  are,  indeed,  indications  of 
the  gulf  and  attempts  to  bridge  it.2  But  upon  the  whole  the  battle 
never  is  fought  out.  On  the  contrary,  Erigena  may  be  said  to  give 
himself  completely  to  each  of  the  two  sides.  And  for  this  he  ought 
not  to  be  condemned  as  a  man  involved  in  mere  self-contradiction. 
For,  in  doing  it,  what  he  really  does  is  to  prophesy  the  Idealism  which 

1  Supra,  pp.  165-175. 

2  Here  and  there  are  statements,  for  instance,  which  remind  one  of  the  device  of 
Plotinus :   It  is  by  no  means  that  of  which  it  is  the  principle.    The  divine  wisdom,  says 
Erigena,  "  without  measure  is  the  measure  of  all,  without  number  is  the  number  of  all, 
without  weight  is  the  weight  or  order  of  all "  (III.  16).    To  the  "grounds  "  of  things— the 
primordial  causes— he  applies  the  distinction  of  Dionysius :  "  first  they  are,  and  then  they 
are  grounds"  (II.  36).    Again  he  frequently  avails  himself  of  a  distinction  that  reminds 
one  of  Mr.  Spencer — the  possibility  of  knowing  that  something  is,  while  it  remains  quite 
impossible  to  know  what  it  is  (e.g.,  III.  28).    Sometimes,  again,  he  declares  that  it  is  a 
"  mystery  " ;  or  appeals  to  the  darkening  of  our  minds  since  the  fall.    But  upon  the  whole, 
as  is  said  in  the  text,  he  simply  leaves  the  two  types  of  thinking  side  by  side.    Indeed,  he 
does  this  in  set  phrase:  "the  ineffable  manifoldness  of  the  divine  unity— for  God  is  in 
Himself  manifold  unity."    (.    .    .    de  ineffdbili  divinae  unitatis  multiplicitate—Deus  est 
enim  unum  multiplex  in  seipso—III.  17). 

286 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

stands  above  both  Mysticism  and  Pantheism,  being  able  by  its  organic 
categories,  to  do  justice  alike  to  the  unity  of  the  divine  nature  and  the 
manifoldness  of  the  world,  .alike  to  the  transcendence  and  the  imman 
ence  of  God.  In  accepting  each  side  as  true  he  really  recognised  that 
truth  was  greater  than  either.1 

The  conception  of  the  procession  or  forthpouring  of  God,  as  the 
source  of  the  universe  of  creatures,  is  everywhere  in  Erigena.  We 
must  be  content,  however,  with  two  passages ;  two  great  passages  one 
would  call  them,  were  it  not  that  the  De  Divisione  Naturae  is  crowded 
from  beginning  to  end  with  such  passages.  One  occurs  about  midway  in 
the  third  Book.  God,  he  says  (following  Dionysius),  cannot  be  called 
this  or  that,  because  He  is  all  and  in  all.  Then  he  goes  on  to  trace 
the  process  in  which  God  goes  beyond  Himself  and  yet  remains  Him 
self.  "  Descending  first  from  the  superessentiality  of  His  nature,  in 
which  He  can  but  be  called  Non-Being,  He  is  created  of  Himself 
[undergoes  a  creation  at  His  own  hands]  in  the  primordial  causes, 
and  becomes  the  beginning  of  every  essence  and  of  all  life,  of  every 
understanding,  and  of  all  things  that  enlightened  contemplation 
perceives  (gnostica  considerat  theoria)  in  the  primordial  causes. 
Then,  descending  out  of  the  primordial  causes,  which  occupy,  as  it 
were,  a  middle  station  between  God  and  the  creature,  that  is,  between 
that  ineffable  superessentiality  which  stands  high  above  every  thought, 
and  the  revealed  Nature  which  is  essentially  cognisable  for  pure  spirits, 

i  It  may  be  advisable— especially  in  view  of  the  loose  and  irresponsible  way  in  which 
the  term  "Pantheism"  i«  frequently  used— to  point  out  once  more  the  exact  relation  of 
the  three  types  of  thought  referred  to  in  the  above  paragraph.  Pantheism  i~  the  extreme 
opposite  of  Mysticism ;  while  Idealism,  when  it  is  really  dominant  and  not  simply  a 
servant  of  some  other  view,  does  justice  to  the  truth  of  both.  Mysticism  sees  reality  as 
an  incommunicable  One  before  which  all  the  apparent  things  of  our  experience  fade  into 
nothingness.  Pantheism  (of  which  Spinoza's  "second  metaphysic"  is  a  type),  on  the 
contrary,  views  God  as  unfolding  Himself  into  a  world  of  particular  things  and  facts,  all 
of  which  therefore  are  real  with  the  reality  of  God,  but  none  of  which  can  be  called 
"individuals,"  since  each  is  simply  a  mode  of  the  one  divine  Substance.  Mysticism,  in  a 
word,  is  the  theology  of  absolute  transcendence.  Pantheism  ihe  theology  of  absolute 
immanence.  While  Idealism  doe^  justice  to  both  the  two  sides  by  viewing  God  as  a  self- 
determining  and  self-communicating  spirit— Himself  a  perfect  individual,  imparting 
Himself  and  so  giving  rise  to  imperfect  or  "created"  individuals.  Again,  Mysticism  is 
negative  theo'ogy;  while  Pantheism  and  Idealism,  though  in  very  different  ways,  are 
affirmative  theologies.  In  dealing  with  the  first  Form  of  Nature,  Erigena  is  a  Mystic;  in 
dealing  wilh  the  second  and  third  Forms,  he  might  almost  be  called  a  combination  of 
Idealist  and  Pantheist ;  and  we  shall  have  later  to  ask  whether  in  dealing  with  the  fourth 
Form,  he  returns  to  the  Mysticism  of  the  first. 

287 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

he  '  becomes }  in  the  effects  of  those  causes,  and  is  made  manifest  in 
His  theophanies.  Thence,  through  the  manifold  forms  of  those  effects, 
He  proceeds,  even  to  that  last  order  of  collective  nature,  in  which 
bodies  are  contained.  And  as  in  this  order  he  goes  forth  into  all 
things,  He  makes  all  and  becomes  all  in  all,  and  returns  into  Himself 
by  calling  all  things  back  into  Himself,  and  while  He  comes  to  be 
[enters  upon  conditioned  existence,  as  one  might  say  in  the  termin 
ology  of  a  modern  school]  in  all  things,  He  does  not  cease  to  be  above 
all.  All  things  He  makes  out  of  nothing,1  inasmuch  as  out  of  His 
superessentiality  He  brings  forth  essences;  living  beings  out  of  His 
exaltation  above  life;  intellects  out  of  His  transcendence  of  the 
intellect;  out  of  the  negation  of  everything  which  is  and  is  not,  the 
affirmation  of  all  that  is  and  is  not.  By  this  also  we  are  most  clearly 
taught  the  return  of  all  things  into  the  cause,  out  of  which  they 
proceeded,  when  all  things  turn  back  again  into  God,  as  air  into  light, 
when  God  will  be  all  in  all ;  not,  indeed,  as  if  God  were  not  even  now 
all  in  all,  but  because,  since  the  transgression  of  human  nature  and  its 
banishment  from  its  seat  in  Eden — that  is  to  say,  from  the  height  of 
the  spiritual  life,  and  from  the  apprehension  of  clearest  wisdom — into 
the  profoundest  deep  of  ignorance,  no  one  save  by  divine  grace  is 
enlightened,  or  is  able — rapt  with  Paul  to  the  height  of  the  hidden 
things  of  God — to  discern  with  the  intent  gaze  of  true  understanding 
how  God  is  all  in  all ;  for  the  cloud  of  fleshly  thoughts  and  the  gloomy 
twilight  of  vain  imaginations  lie  between,  and  the  penetrating  genius 
of  the  soul,  weakened  by  unreasoning  passions  and  baffled  by  the 
splendours  of  transparent  truth,  expends  itself  upon  the  accustomed 
shadows  of  the  corporeal  world.  For  it  is  not  open  to  us  to  believe 
that  the  heavenly  essences,  who  never  have  left  their  state  of  eternal 
blessedness,  can  recognise  in  the  whole  of  creation  anything  else  but 
only  God  Himself,  since  they,  lifted  high  above  all  sense  and  thought, 
see  all  things  in  God  and  in  the  primordial  causes,  without  needing  any 

i  For  this  "nothing,"  it  will  of  course  be  understood,  Erigena  has  a  meaning.  The 
"  nothing"  out  of  which  the  world  is  made,  he  proves  (III.  20-23)  to  be  the  superessential 
God  Himself.  For  "all  things  have  their  becoming  from  God  and  through  God  and  in 
God  "  ;  and  if  God  is  to  be  viewed  as  cause  and  the  world  as  effect,  then  "  there  does  not 
pass  over  from  the  cause  into  its  effects  anything  which  is  alien  to  the  true  and  proper 
nature  of  the  cause." 

288 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

work  of  nature  for  the  knowledge  of  truth, — for  they  alone  enjoy  the 
ineffable  grace  of  the  eternal  light."1 

The  other,  and  more  extended,  of  the  two  passages  occurs  earlier 
in  the  third  Book.  Erigena  is  dealing  with  the  "  participation  "  which 
exists  among  the  orders  of  natural  being.  But  before  taking  this 
passage  we  should  note  the  express  definition  of  "  participation  "  given 
in  another  chapter.  All  things  that  are,  says  Erigena — following 
"  that  supreme  theologian,  Dionysius  the  Areopagite,  illustrious 
bishop  of  Athens " — all  things  that  are  and  all  things  that  are 
not,  are  to  be  understood  as  nothing  other  than  participation  in 
the  divine  essence.  This  participation  is  itself  nothing  other  than 
the  reception  or  assumption  of  the  essence  which  is  participated 
in;  and  such  reception  implies,  or  rather  is,  the  "pouring  out 
of  the  divine  wisdom  which  is  to  all  things  their  substance  and 
their  essence  and  whatever  under  the  form  of  nature  is  to  be 
perceived  in  them."2  But  in  the  passage  which  we  are  now  to 
consider  Erigena  is  thinking  of  that  participation  as  the  principle  of 
the  ordering  of  the  whole  universe.  Each  order  of  natural  being 
participates  in  that  which  is  above  it  and  is  participated  in  by  that 
below  it ;  except  that  God,  who  is  highest,  is  participated  in,  but  does 
not  participate;  while  "bodies/7  which  are  lowest,  participate,  but 
are  not  participated  in.  From  their  original  ground  in  the  divine 
Wisdom,  the  orders  of  being  descend  in  a  series  of  natural  gradations ; 
among  their  "  participations "  the  all-creative  wisdom  "  has  estab 
lished  wonderful  and  ineffable  harmonies  by  which  all  things  are 
brought  to  the  accord  and  friendship,  or  to  the  peace  and  love,  or  to 
whatever  else  be  the  true  name  for  this  unifying  of  all  things."  But 
what  can  this  "  participation  "  be  ?  It  is  nothing  other,  is  the  answer, 
than  the  derivation  of  a  next-following  essence  from  that  which 
precedes  it,  and  the  bestowal  of  being  from  a  first  to  that  which  stands 
next  to  it.  And  then  Erigena  goes  on  to  show  how,  through  such 
bestowal,  the  orders  of  the  universe  have  their  being.  As  a  river 

1  III.  20. 

2  III.  9.— The  Master  goes  on  to  call  the  Scholar's  attention  to  the  opinion  of  Dionysius 
de  processione  Dei  per  omnia,  et  mansione  in  seipso,  in  a  letter  to  Titus  the  priest  who 
had  asked  what  the  house  of  Wisdom  is,  and  what  its  mixing-bowl  and  its  meat  and 
drink. 

20  289 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

streams  from  its  source,,  and  its  waters  for  ever  and,  without  loss  of 
continuity  make  their  way  downward  through  the  longest  channel,  so 
"  the  divine  goodness,  and  essence,  arid  life,  and  wisdom,  and  all  that 
in  the  source  of  all  exists,  pour  forth,  first  in  the  primordial  causes, 
and  make  these  to  be;  and  then  hasten  down,  in  some  ineffable  way, 
through  the  primordial  causes  into  the  effects  of  these,  through  the 
self-harmonious  orders  of  the  universe,  always  flowing  down  through 
the  higher  to  the  lower;  and  return  by  the  most  secret  pores  of  nature, 
and  by  the  most  hidden  path,  to  their  source  again.  From  that  source 
is  every  good  thing,  every  essence,  all  life,  all  sense,  all  reason,  all 
wisdom,  every  genus,  every  species,  all  beauty,  all  order,  all  unity,  all 
equality,  all  difference,  all  place,  all  time,  both  everything  which  is 
and  everything  which  is  not,  both  everything  which  is  thought  and 
everything  which  is  perceived  by  sense  and  everything  which  is  above 
sense  and  thought.  The  immutable  motion  in  itself  of  the  highest 
and  triune  and  sole  true  goodness,  and  its  simple  multiplicity,  and  its 
inexhaustible  pouring  forth  from  itself,  in  itself,  to  itself,  are  the 
cause  of  all  things,  nay  rather,  are  all  things.  For  if  the  being  thought 
of  all  things  (intellectus  omnium]  is  all  things,  and  if  the  divine 
goodness  alone  thinks  all  things,  then  that  divine  goodness  itself  is 
alone  all  things,  because  it  is  the  sole  gnostic  power  which  knew 
all  things  before  they  were  all  things,  and  knew  all  things  not 
outside  of  itself — for  outside  of  itself  there  is  nothing — but  has 
all  things  within  itself.  For  it  encompasses  all  things,  and  nothing 
is  within  it,  in  so  far  as  it  is  true,  but  itself,  because  it  alone  is 
true.  The  other  things  which  are  said  to  be,  are  its  theophanies, 
which  truly  subsist  in  it.  And  so  God  is  everything  which  truly 
is,  because  He  Himself  makes  all  things  and  becomes  in  all  things, 
as  saith  St.  Dionysius  the  Areopagite.  For  everything" — here 
Erigena  exhausts  the  power  of  metaphor  in  insisting  that  the  world 
which  is  known  is  the  manifestation  of  the  God  who  cannot  be 
known — "  everything  which  is  thought  or  perceived  by  sense  is 
nothing  other  than  the  appearance  of  Him  who  does  not  appear,  the 
manifestation  of  the  hidden,  the  affirmation  of  the  denied,  the  compre 
hension  of  the  incomprehensible,  the  utterance  of  the  ineffable,  the 
approach  of  the  inaccessible,  the  apprehension  of  the  unintelligible, 

290 


EBIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

the  body  of  the  incorporeal,,  the  essence  of  that  which  is  above  essence, 
the  form  of  that  which  has  no  form,  the  measure  of  the  immeasurable, 
the  number  of  the  innumerable,  the  weight  of  that  which  is  devoid  of 
weight,  the  coming  into  gross  matter  of  the  spiritual,  the  visibility  of 
the  invisible,  the  possession  of  place  by  that  which  is  beyond  place,  the 
taking  on  of  time-form  by  that  which  is  above  time,  the  denning  of 
the  infinite,  the  circumscribing  of  that  which  cannot  be  compassed, 
and  whatever  else  is  thought  or  comprehended  by  pure  intellect,  or 
cannot  be  held  within  the  bounds  of  memory,  or  escapes  the  pene 
trating  insight  of  the  soul/'1  Then  Erigena  goes  on  to  show,  in  the 
most  interesting  way,  that  we  men  have  in  our  own  nature  as  intelli 
gences,  an  example  of  precisely  such  an  activity  of  self-manifestation. 
Alone,  invisible,  absolute  in  itself,  our  thought  is  yet  able  to  go  forth 
from  itself,  and  to  incorporate  itself  in  sounds  and  signs,  and  to  enter 
into  the  depth  of  others'  hearts,  and  mingle  itself  with  other  minds, 
and  become  one  with  that  to  which  it  is  joined — and  yet  it  remains 
always  itself,  and  in  uniting  itself  with  others  does  not  relinquish  its 
own  simplicity.  But  this  brings  us  to  an  aspect  of  Erigena's  thought 
(his  Idealism)  which  we  are  not  yet  in  position  to  discuss.  What  we 
have  at  this  point  to  consider  is  something  very  different :  namely,  that 
when  Erigena  proceeds  to  work  out  his  view  of  the  universe  in  its 
descending  scale  of  existences  as  arising  from  an  outflowing,  a  pouring 
forth,  of  itself  on  the  part  of  the  divina  bonitas,  he  is  in  much  better 
position  than  Plotinus.  His  view  of  the  absolute  unity  and  transcend 
ence  of  God  places  him,  at  the  beginning,  in  the  same  logical  situation 
as  Plotinus,  and  with  the  same  difficulties  to  face.  But  he  inherited 
that  which  Plotinus  did  not ;  the  tradition  of  Christian  theology.  And 
this  in  a  form  peculiarly  favourable  to  his  endeavour}  for  the  theology 
to  which  he  turned  by  affinity  of  soul,  was  that  last  great  world-labour 
of  the  Greek  spirit,  the  theology  of  the  East.  True,  he  quotes  contin 
ually  from  the  Areopagite  and  from  Maximus  the  Confessor;  but  he 
constructs  no  fantastic  hierarchy;  a  singularly  clear  and  piercing 
reason  guides  him,  even  when  he  is  denying  that  reason  can  know 
ultimate  reality.  True,  again,  he  could  not  live  in  the  West  and  escape 
Augustine's  influence;  yet  he  is  able  to  deal  critically  even  with 

i  in.  i. 
291 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

Augustine.  But  the  man  to  whom  really  he  reaches  his  hands  across 
the  ages  is  Origen.  And  the  theology  which  really  had  power  over  his 
mind  was  that  theology  whose  central  and  determinative  conception  is 
the  idea  of  the  divine  nature  manifesting  itself  in  the  Word.  This 
theology  of  the  Logos  and  the  Trinity  it  is  that  guides  Erigena  in  this 
greater  half  of  his  thought  which  sees  the  incommunicable  One  as  the 
God  who  goes  forth  from  Himself,,  communicates  Himself,  and  gives 
rise  to  a  universe  which  in  the  ordered  scale  of  its  existences  is  full  of 
harmony  and  beauty,  and  in  its  natural  arrangements  testifies  of 
spiritual  truths.  So  that  Erigena  is  able  to  bring  to  the  difficulties 
that  beset  him  and  Plotinus  alike,  a  solution  which  tends  as  truly  to 
be  concrete  as  that  of  Plotinus  to  be  abstract.  Where  Plotinus  is 
compelled  to  deal  in  abstract  Ideas,  Erigena  deals  in  living  energies, 
living  powers,  living  affections.  The  system  of  Erigena  comes,  in 
fact,  to  be  a  Neo-Platonic  framework  filled  with  Idealistic  content. 

The  second  Book  is  formally  given  to  the  consideration  of  "  the 
procession  of  the  creatures  from  the  first  and  unitary  cause  of  all 
things  through  the  primordial  essences  (which,  before  all  things,  are 
established  by  it  and  in  it  and  through  it)  into  the  diverse  classes,  and 
forms,  and  numbers,  of  things,  to  infinity."1  At  the  same  time — so 
the  Master  warns  the  Disciple — we  shall  find  in  the  course  of  that 
discussion  many  a  thing  introduced  about  the  return  of  the  creatures 
to  their  beginning  and  goal ;  for  the  procession  and  the  return  of  the 
creatures  are  so  intimately  connected  as  to  appear  inseparable;  about 
the  procession  nothing  worthy  or  reliable  can  be  advanced  without  at 
the  same  time  considering  the  return  of  the  creatures  and  the  final 
unifying  of  all  things.  Then  the  Master  begins  the  discussion  of  the 
first  stage  of  the  outgoing  of  the  divine  nature  in  this  way :  "  As  the 
second  Form  of  universal  Nature,  there  appears  (enitet,  shines  forth), 
as  was  said  above,  that  which  is  created  and  creates,  and  which  accord 
ing  to  my  belief  is  to  be  understood  as  consisting  only  in  the 
primordial  causes  of  things.  These  primordial  causes  of  things  are 
called  by  the  Greeks  TtpwroTVTta,  that  is,  primordial  patterns,  or 
TrpoopiGfAara, that  is,  predestinations  or  determinings  (definitiones)  ; 
or  again,  Oeia  OeXr/jjara,  that  is,  divine  volitions;  and  also  ideal, 

1  IT.  2. 

292 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

that  is,  kinds  or  forms  in  which  the  unchangeable  grounds  of  all 
things  to  be  created,  were  already  present.  Concerning  these  we  shall 
speak  more  in  detail  in  the  course  of  our  work,  and  bring  forward 
testimonies  from  the  holy  Fathers.  Not  wrongly,  however,  are  they 
called  by  those  names ;  for  the  Father,  that  is,  the  beginning  and  origin 
of  all  things,  constituted  already  in  His  Word  (namely,  in  the  only- 
begotten  Son)  the  grounds  of  all  things  which  were  to  be  created, 
before  he  constituted  them  into  genera,  and  species,  and  numbers,  and 
differences,  and  all  those  other  things  which  in  created  Nature  either 
can  be  seen  and  are  seen,  or  on  account  of  their  loftiness  cannot  be 
seen,  and  are  not  seen,,  but  none  the  less  are/'1 

The  original  forms,  then — the  beginnings,  the  causes,  the  Ideas — 
of  all  things,  the  Father  constituted  in  the  Son.  And  constituted  them 
eternally.  "  What  is  to  be  gathered/'  Erigena  asks,  te  from  that  word 
of  the  theologian:  In  the  beginning  God  created?  Art  thou  to  under 
stand  from  these  words,  that  the  Father  first  begot  His  Word,  and 
then  made  the  heavens  and  the  earth  in  Him?  Or  has  He  begotten 
His  Word  eternally,  and  in  Him  eternally  made  all  things,  so  that  the 
procession  of  the  Word  from  the  Father,  through  begetting,  in  no  wise 
goes  before  that  procession  of  all  things  out  of  nothing  which  is 
accomplished  in  the  Word  through  creation?  Or,  to  put  it  more 
plainly:  have  the  primordial  causes  not  always  been  in  the  Word  of 
God  in  which  they  have  been  made?  and  was  the  Word  when  as  yet  the 
causes  were  not?  Or  are  they  co-eternal  with  Him,  so  that  the  Word 
never  existed  without  the  causes  which  have  their  ground  in  Him?  and 
is  then  that  which  is  said  of  a  precedence  of  the  Word  to  the  causes 
grounded  in  Him,  spoken  altogether  in  the  sense,  that  the  Word 
creates  the  causes,  and  they  by  the  Word  and  in  the  Word  are  created  ?'3 
The  decision  is  in  favour  of  the  latter  view;  "for,"  as  the  Disciple 
says,  "  I  do  not  see  how  a  begetting  of  the  Word  from  the  Father  can: 
precede  in  time  the  creation  of  all  things  from  the  Father  in  the  Word 
and  through  the  Word.  Rather  I  must  believe  that  the  begetting  of 
the  Word  and  the  creation  of  all  things  in  the  Word,  are  co-eternal, 
since  no  one  can  be  right  in  believing  that  in  God  there  is  anything 
accidental  or  any  temporal  motions  or  processions.  .  .  .  Since  to 

1  II.  2 

293 


EfilGENA.:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

God  it  is  not  accidental  to  be  the  Beginning,  therefore  He  was  never 
without  that  of  which  He  is  the  beginning."1  And  the  primordial 
causes  which  are  thus  eternal  in  the  Word  are  likewise.,  in  that  Word, 
both  one  and  many,  both  a  unity  and  a  manifold.  A  passage  in  the 
third  Book  in  which  this  unity-in-diversity  of  the  primordial  causes 
is  set  forth,  is  specially  interesting  both  for  itself  and  for  the  argu 
ment  which  it  concludes.2  The  Disciple  is  in  a  perplexity:  in  the 
unbegotten  Word,  or  Wisdom,  of  the  Father  the  primordial  causes  are 
eternal;  in  that  Word  or  Wisdom,  too,  all  things  that  proceed  are 
eternal;  then  how  can  the  world  have  been  created,  as  the  church 
teaches  us,  out  of  nothing?  For  how  can  anything  be  eternal,  which 
was  not  before  it  originated  ?  And  how  can  that  be  in  eternity  which 
begins  to  be  in  and  with  time?  The  Disciple,  following  a  line  of 
thought  which  is  present  in  Plato  and  Aristotle,  is  inclined  to  take 
refuge  in  a  theory  of  "  formless  matter/'  The  primordial  causes  are 
eternal  in  the  Wisdom  of  the  Father ;  but  the  formless  matter  in  and 
through  which  those  causes  pass  over  into  their  effects — i.e.,  into  the 
genera  and  species  of  which  the  world  is  made  up — is  not  thus  eternal 
in  God,  and  is  not  to  be  numbered  among  the  active  "  causes."  But 
Erigena  sees  clearly  that  if  such  formless  matter  plays  a  part  in  the 
constituting  of  the  world,  it  must  also  be  numbered  among  the  causes 
which  are  eternal  in  God;  and  points  out  the  contradiction  in  the 
position  of  the  "  secular  philosophers  "  who  make  formless  matter  a 
principle  outside  of  God  and  co-eternal  with  Him.  He  gives  them 
credit  for  taking  up  such  a  position  out  of  their  high  conception  of 
God,  as  a  being  who  can  have  no'  connexion  with  formless  matter.  But 
his  own  vision  is  more  comprehensive  and  more  daring:  both  the 
formlessness  of  things,  and  their  forms,  with  everything,  whether 
essential  or  accidental,  which  those  forms  contain,  are  created  of  the 
-one  All-cause.  From  the  one  universal  ground  or  source  everything 
which  is,  and  which  is  not,  flows  forth:  whether  in  the  primordial 
causes  which,  at  once  and  all  together  (semel  et  simul),  eternally  are 
made  in  the  only-begotten  Word  of  God;  or  in  the  formless  matter 
from  which  the  primordial  causes  have  taken  occasion  to  appear  in 
visible  creation;  or  in  the  effects  of  those  primordial  causes — effects 

1  II.  20.  2  HI.  5.9. 

294 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

in  which  this  world  from  its  beginning  to  its  end  runs  its  course  in 
natural  order  under  the  guidance  of  divine  providence.  But  this  only 
shifts  the  Disciple's  perplexity  into  another  quarter.  How  can  the 
world  be  eternal  in  God  when  Eternity  and  Becoming  stand  opposed? 
That  which  becomes  stands  in  antithesis  to  that  which  is  eternal: 
how.,  then,  can  the  world  be  at  once  eternal  and  yet  in  process  of 
becoming?  In  reply  it  is  pointed  out  that  in  God  there  is  nothing 
accidental.  Therefore,  if  He  is  Creator,,  He  is  not  so  accidentally; 
it  must  be  of  the  essence  of  His  nature  to  be  Creator;  and,  therefore, 
He  is  Creator  eternally.  That  which  is  eternal,  therefore,  and  that 
which  has  come  to  be,  are  not  diverse,  but  are  one  and  the  same;  in 
the  Word  of  God,  the  universe  is  eternal,  and  yet  it  is  at  the  same 
time  a  process  of  becoming.1  Then  Erigena  sums  up  the  argument 
with  a  statement  to  this  effect. — The  grounds  of  all  things,  so  far  as 
they  are  understood  in  the  superessential  nature  of  the  Word,  are 
eternal.  For  whatever  exists  substantially  in  the  divine  Word,  just 
because  it  is  nothing  other  than  the  Word  itself,  must  necessarily  be 
eternal.  So,  then,  the  Word  itself  and  the  unitary  and  yet  manifold 
highest  ground  of  the  whole  created  universe  are  one  and  the  same. 
The  only-begotten  Son  of  God  is,  as  the  term  AGIOS'  indicates,  at  once 
Word  and  ground  and  cause :  the  Word,  for  through  Him  the  Father 
spoke  the  becoming  of  all  things;  the  ground,  for  He  Himself  is  the 
first  exemplar  [the  Idea]  of  the  whole  visible  and  invisible  universe — 
in  Him  the  Father  saw  all  that  He  willed  to  come  to  be,  before  it  had 

i  Cf.  III.  16.  "...  all  things  visible  and  invisible,  eternal  and  timeless,  and  eternity 
itself,  and  time,  and  places,  and  distances,  and  all  that  is  named  under  the  categories  of  sub 
stance  or  of  accident,  and  in  general  terms  what  things  soever  the  whole  created  universe 
contains,  are  at  once,  in  the  only-begotten  Word  of  God,  both  eternal  and  made.  In  them 
neither  does  the  eternity  precede  the  becoming,  nor  the  becoming  the  eternity;  the 
eternity  is  created  and  the  being  created  is  eternal  in  the  dispensation  of  the  Word.  For 
all  things  which  in  the  order  of  the  ages  seem  to  come  temporally  or  spatially  into  being 
through  generation  have  eternally  been  made,  all  together  and  at  once,  in  the  Word  of  the 
Lord.  It  is  not  to  be  believed  that  they  first  begin  to  be  when  their  arising  in  this  world 
is  perceived."  Substantially  they  were  always  in  the  Word  of  the  Lord ;  and  their  arising, 
and  perishing  in  the  order  of  space  and  time  through  generation,  that  is,  through  the 
reception  of  the  accidental,  was  always  in  the  Word  of  God,  in  which  that  which  is  to 
become  already  has  become.  The  divine  Wisdom  includes  all  times,  so  that  everything 
which  in  the  nature  of  things  has  a  temporal  origin,  in  it  precedes  and  eternally  subsists. 
For  it  without  measure  is  the  measure  of  all,  without  number  is  the  number  of  all,  with 
out  weight  is  the  weight  or  order  of  all ;  nay,  is  time  and  age,  is  past  and  present  and 
future." 

295 


EBIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

yet  become ;  the  cause,  for  the  occasions  to  all  things  subsist  eternally 
and  unchangeably  in  Him.  And  since  the  Son  of  God  is  thus  Word 
and  ground  and  cause,  it  is  not  inappropriate  to  say :  the  unitary  and 
yet  in  itself  infinitely  manifold  creative  ground  and  cause  of  the  whole 
created  universe,  is  the  Word  of  God ;  or  conversely,  the  Word  of  C  od 
is  the  unitary  and  yet  in  itself  infinitely  manifold  creative  ground  and 
cause  of  the  created  universe.  Unitary  (simplex),  because  the  totality 
of  all  things  in  Him  is  indivisible  and  inseparable;  assuredly  the 
Word  of  God  is  the  indivisible  and  inseparable  unity  of  all  things, 
because  He  Himself  is  all  things.  Manifold,  however,  it  may  also 
without  incorrectness  be  called,  because  it  pours  itself  out  to  infinity 
through  all  things ;  and  this  outpouring  is  itself  the  subsistence  of  all 
things,  for  "  it  reaches  from  end  to  end  sweetly  and  strongly  ordering 
all  things"  (as  is  declared  in  the  Psalm:  velociter  currit  sermo  ejus). 
The  Word  remains  comprehended  in  itself  and  unitary,  because  in  it 
all  things  are  one.  While  it  remains  in  itself  as  something  complete, 
and  more  than  complete,  and  separate  from  all  things,  yet  it  extends 
itself  into  all  things,  and  that  extension  of  itself  is  all  things.  The 
outpouring,  or  extension,  or  "  running  "  of  the  Word  goes  [logically] 
before  all  things,  and  is  the  cause  of  the  existence  of  all  things,  and  is 
all  things.  For,  as  Erigena  emphatically  says,  there  could  be  no  more 
despicable  and  pitiable  death  of  the  rational  soul  than  even  to  think, 
concerning  the  All-creator,  such  an  abominable  monstrosity  as  that 
there  is  a  space  or  time  (or,  he  might  have  added,  matter)  already 
prepared  out  into  which  the  Word  of  God  in  its  creative  activity 
proceeds. 

This  belief  that  God  eternally  constituted  the  primordial  causes  in 
the  Word,  and  that  in  the  Word  they  are  one,  stands  central  to 
Erigena's  theory  of  the  world  and  its  derivation  from  God.  He  does 
not  deal  explicitly  with  the  relation  of  the  Word  to  the  original  c.id 
ultimate  God,  nor  with  the  question  whether  that  ultimate  God  has 
manifested  or  communicated  Himself  in  the  Word.  Such  a  question 
could  but  be  ruled  out  of  court  by  a  theologian  who  with  regard  to  the 
first  and  ultimate  God  follows  the  via  negativa.1  So  that  with  regard 

i  After  the  formal  transition  from  negative  to  affirmative  theology  in  the  passage 
quoted  above  (11.30;  see  p.  283  supra),  Erigena  turns  directly  to  the  doctrine  of  the 
Trinity  and  goes  on  to  say  that  the  Father  may  not  inappropriately  be  identified  with  the 

296 


EBIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

to  the  three  difficulties  of  Plotinus  mentioned  above,  we  must  say  that 
the  first  stands  also  for  Erigena;  stands,  in  fact,  for  all  negative 
theology  whatsoever.  At  the  same  time  it  should  be  pointed  out  that 
Erigena,  inheriting  and  employing  in  the  way  just  noted  the  Logos- 
doctrine  of  Greek  theology,  needed  but  to  go  one  step  farther  than  he 
actually  did — needed  but  to  view  the  Logos  as  not  only  the  principle 
of  unity  of  the  second  Form,  but  as  also  its  principle  of  relation  with 
the  first — in  order  to  overcome  the  negative  theology  altogether.  But 
that  was  not  to  be  expected.  With  Erigena — as  with  many  of  the 
greatest  medieval  theologians — to  give  up  the  negative  theology  would 
have 'been  to  give  up  half  of  his  soul.  But  when  once  he  has  passed 
from  the  first  Form  of  Nature  to  the  second,  it  illuminates  the  whole 
way  for  him.  It  enables  him  to  solve  at  once  what  we  have  called  the 
second  difficulty  of  Plotinus ;  for  he  can  view  the  causae  primordiales, 
the  Ideas,  as  one  in  Christ ;  in  Him  the  ideal  world,  the  second  Form 
of  Nature,  consists  ;l  He  is  the  living  principle  of  synthesis  in  which 
the  primordial  causes^-are  at  once  many  and  one.1  <: 

"cause  of  causes."  There  are  other  passages  which  seem  to  touch  upon  this;  but  they 
really  deal  with  the  inner  relationships  of  the  Trinity.  Eckhart's  problem  of  the  relation 
of  God  (the  Trinity)  to  the  Godhead— which  is  precisely  the  problem  at  issue  here— Erigena 
does  not  face.  Indeed,  as  already  has  been  pointed  oiit,  his  treatment  of  the  first  Form  of 
Nature,  if  it  be  allowed  to  stand,  absolves  him  from  the  obligation  to  deal  with  it. 

i  How  this  can  be,  Erigena  bluntly  confesses  that  he  does  not  know.  "How  all  things 
have  their  ground  in  the  Word  of  God,  let  him  explain  who  can.  I  confess  that  I  do  not 
know.  And  I  am  not  ashamed  not  to  know,  when  I  hear  the  Apostle  say  Qui  solus  habes 
immortalitatem,  et  lucem  habitas  inaccessibilcm, — just  as  if  he  were  aiming  from  far  afe 
our  present  investigation."  (III.  16.) 

What  is  really  behind  such  a  statement  is  the  fact  that  Erigena  is  not  able  to  use  the 
organic  categories  to  show  how  a  spiritual  system  is  both  a  many  and  a  one.  And  a  still 
graver  evidence  of  the  same  fact  is  the  way  in  which  Erigena  at  times  almost  loses  the 
manifoldness  of  the  Ideas  or  primordial  causes  in  their  unity.  "The  grounds  of  the 
things  which  God  has  created  in  Himself  (i.e.,  which  the  Father  has  created  in  the  Son) 
are"— so  Erigrna  takes  for  granted  in  the  course  of  one  of  his  arguments— "one  in  Him 
without  division  ;  they  admit  no  defining  of  the  proper  substance  through  proper  differ 
entiae  or  through  accidental  determinations,  for  it  is  only  in  their  effects,  not  in  themselves, 
that  they  suffer  these."  (II.  28.)  "  In  themselves  the  first  causes  are  one,  and  simple,  and 
through  no  known  order  determined  or  separated  from  one  another  ;  such  determination 
or  separation  they  undergo  in  their  effects.  Even  as  in  the  unit,  while  in  it  all  the 
particular  numbers  by  one  principle  subsist,  yet  no  single  number  is  distinguished  from 
another,  since  in  it  they  are  a  unity,  and  a  simple  unity,  and  not  a  unity  compounded  of 
many  members  (for  while  out  of  the  unit  all  the  multiplication  of  the  numbers  proceeds 
to  infinity,  yet  the  unit  is  by  no  means  composed  of  the  manifold  numbers  which  proceed 
from  it,  as  if  by  a  sort  of  counting  the>e  together  into  one) :— even  so  the  primordial 
causes,  while  they  are  understood  as  contained  in  the  principle  of  all  things,  that  is  to  say, 
in  the  only-begotten  (al.  unbegjtten)  Word  of  God,  are  a  simple  and  undivided  unity  ;  as 

297 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

And  it  likewise  places  within  his  reach  a  solution  of  what  was 
noted  as  the  third  difficulty  of  Plotimis.  The  existence  of  the 
primordial  causes  in  the  Word  makes  it  easy  to  view  them  as  having 
a  living  and  a  creative  energy,  such  as  enables  them  to  proceed  beyond 
themselves  and  give  rise  to  the  particular  things  and  beings  of  our 
present  world.  Or,  rather,  it  is  the  Word  itself  that  in  them,  proceeds 
to  another  stage  in  its  outpouring  of  itself,1  and  gives  rise  to  another 
order  of  natural  existences — to  what  Erigena  calls  the  third  Form  of 
Nature. 

At  the  close  of  the  second  Book  there  is  a  passage  which  sums  up 
Erigena's  view  of  the  second  Form  of  Nature  as  a  world  of  ideal 
energies  lying  between  the  ultimate  reality  and  our  present  order  of 
things,  and  also  indicates  the  transition  between  those  Ideas  and  the 
present  world;  a  passage  which  is  interesting,  also,  as  showing  with 
special  distinctness  the  blending  in  Erigena  of  the  two  great  labours 
which  the  Greek  spirit  performed  after  it  had  been  driven  from  its 
home  and  was  losing  itself  among  the  Gentiles — the  theology  of 
Plotinus,  the  theology  of  Nica?a.  "  The  primordial  causes,  then,  as  I 
said  before,  are  what  the  Greeks  call  Ideas ;  that  is,  the  eternal  species 
or  forms  and  the  unchangeable  principles  after  which  and  in  which 
the  world  visible  and  invisible  is  formed  and  governed.  Hence  by 
the  Greek  sages  they  came  rightly  to  be  called  TrpoororvTra,  that  is, 
original  types  or  pattern-forms,  which  the  Father  made  in  the  Son, 
and  which  l>y  the  Holy  Ghost  are  distributed  into  their  effects  and 
made  manifold.  They  are  called,  too,  Trpoopicr/uara,  that  is,  predeter 
minations  (or  foreordinations) ;  for  in  them  whatever  things  by  divine 

soon,  however,  as  they  proceed  into  their  infinitely  manifold  effects,  they  take  on  their 
vast  and  orderly  plurality;  not  as  if  the  cause  of  all  things  were  not  also  order  and 
arrangement,  or  as  if  arrangement  in  itself  were  not  to  be  counted  among  the  principles 
of  things,  when  it  is  by  participation  in  it  that  all  orderly  things  receive  their  order;  but 
because  every  order  appears  as  one  and  simple,  and  is  distinguished  by  no  differences,  in 
the  highest  All-cause  and  in  the  first  participation  in  it,  where  all  orders  are  unvarying 
from  themselves,  forming  an  indissoluble  unity  whence  the  manifold  order  of  all  things 
flows  down."  (III.  1.) 

i  Not  only,  Erigena  urges  (e.g.  in  III.  16),  are  all  things  at  once  eternal  and  "become" 
(facta)  in  the  divine  Word,  but  the  divine  Word  itself  makes  everything  and  in  everything 
becomes.  It  alone  is  the  essence  of  the  existent,  the  movement  and  separation  of  things 
that  are  distinct,  the  indissoluble  connexion  of  the  mingled  and  compounded,  the 
foundation  of  the  established  ;  in  a  word,  in  all  things  it  becomes  all. 

298 

\) 

\] 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

providence  are  coming  to  be  or  have  come  to  be  or  shall  come  to  be 
are  all  together  and  at  once  and  unchangeably  predestined.  For 
nothing  in  the  visible  and  invisible  creature  arises  in  natural  wise 
except  what  in  them  before  all  times  and  places  is  predetermined  and 
foreordained.  In  like  manner,  they  are  wont  to  be  called  by  philoso 
phers  Oeia  6s Xr//j<xTa,  that  is,  divine  volitions;  for  all  things  that 
God  willed  to  make,  He  made  in  them  primordially  and  causally ;  and 
all  things  that  are  to  come  into  being,  came  into  being  in  them  before 
the  ages.  And,  therefore,  they  are  said  to  be  the  principles  of  all 
things,  because  all  things  that  in  the  creature,  whether  visible  or 
invisible,  are  perceived  by  sense  or  thought,  subsist  by  participation  in 
them.  They  themselves,  however,  are  participations  in  the  one  All- 
cause,  the  highest  and  holy  Trinity,  and  hence  are  said  to  exist  in 
themselves,  because  between  them  and  the  one  cause  of  all  things  no 
creature  intervenes.  And  while  they  subsist  unchangeably  in  it,  they 
are  the  primordial  causes  of  other  causes  which  follow  upon  them  to 
the  uttermost  limits  of  the  whole  created  and  infinitely  manifolded 
Nature ;  "  infinitely,"  I  say,  not  in  respect  of  the  Creator,  but  of  the 
creature — for  the  end  of  the  multiplication  of  the  creatures  is  known 
to  the  Creator  alone,  because  He  Himself  and  no  other  is  that  end. 
These  primordial  causes,  then,  which  divine  sages  call  the  principles 
of  all  things,  are  Goodness  in  itself,  Essence  in  itself,  Life  in  itself, 
Wisdom  in  itself,  Truth  in  itself,  Thought  in  itself,  and  so  with  Reason, 
Power,  Righteousness,  Welfare,  Magnitude,  Omnipotence,  Eternity, 
Peace,  and  all  the  powers  and  principles,  which  all  together  and  at  once 
the  Father  made  in  the  Son,  and  according  to  which  the  order  of  all 
things  from  the  highest  to  the  lowest  is  framed  (texitur), — that  is, 
from  the  intellectual  creature  which,  after  God,  is  nearest  to  God, 
down  to  that  last  order  of  all  things  in  which  bodies  are  contained. 
For  that  which  is  good  is  so  through  participation  in  the  Good  in 
itself ;  that  which  subsists  essentially  and  substantially  subsists  through 
participation  in  Essence  in  itself;  that  which  lives  possesses  life 
through  participation  in  Life  in  itself.  So,  too,  that  which  is  wise  and 
intelligent  and  reasonable,  is  so  only  through  participation  in  Wisdom 
in  itself,  Intelligence  in  itself,  Reason  in  itself.  And  the  same  of  the 
others.  For  there  is  in  Nature  no  power,  whether  universal  or 

299 


EEIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

particular,  which  does  not  proceed,  by  an  ineffable  participation,  from 
the  primordial  causes/'1 

The  position  indicated  in  the  italicised  words  of  the  foregoing 
passage,  Erigena  makes  more  explicit  elsewhere.  Father,  Son,  and 
Holy  Ghost,  he  says,  are  three  causes  in  one  cause.  The  Father  is 
the  begetting  cause  of  the  only-begotten  Son,  who  on  His  side  "  is 
the  cause  of  all  the  primordial  causes,  which  in  Him  are  created  by 
the  Father.  The  same  Father  is  the  cause  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  who 
proceeds  from  Him  through  the  Son,  and  the  Holy  Ghost  in  turn  is 
the  cause  of  the  dividing,  manifolding,  and  distributing,  of  all  the 
causes  created  by  the  Father  in  the  Son,  into  their  universal,  special, 
and  proper  effects,  according  to  Nature  and  according  to  Grace."2  Or 
again,  in  another  connexion,  "  If,  then,  there  is  nothing  to  be  perceived 
in  the  nature  of  created  things  except  what  is  given  them  by  the 
Creator,  it  follows  that  the  creature,  with  regard  alike  to  its  essence 
and  its  accidents,  is  nothing  other  than  a  gift  of  the  Creator ;  and  the 
dispensation  of  the  gifts  theology  ascribes  to  the  Holy  Ghost  as  His 
peculiar  function.  All,  therefore,  that  the  Father  does  in  the  Son,  the 
Holy  Ghost  dispenses,  and,  as  He  will,  divides  to  each  thing  its  own. 
Seest  thou  not,  then,  how  theology  is  able  to  attribute  severally  to  the 
substances  or  persons  of  the  divine  Goodness,  as  it  were,  their  special 
properties?  The  Father  (so  it  affirms)  does  all;  in  the  Word, 
universally,  essentially,  and  simply,  all  the  primordial  causes  of  things 
have  eternally  their  origin;  the  primordial  causes  originating  in  the 
AYord,  the  Spirit  distributes,  like  seeds  with  power  of  growth,  into 
their  effects — i.e.,  into  the  genera  and  species,  the  numbers  and  distinc 
tions,  whether  of  celestial  and  spiritual  essences  altogether  without 
bodies,  or  of  essences  clad  with  purest  spiritual  bodies  constituted  of 
the  simplicity  of  the  universal  elements,  or  of  the  sensible  existences  of 
this  visible  world — existences  universal  or  particular,  separate  in 
space,  movable  in  time,  differing  in  quality  and  quantity."3  And  this 
view  of  the  function  of  the  Holy  Ghost  as  one  of  the  persons  of  the 
Trinity,  can  be  proven,  as  Erigena  remarks  (a  few  sentences  before 
the  passage  just  quoted),  from  the  testimony  of  the  Apostle  (Alii  per 
S.piritum  datur  sermo  sapientiae ,  alii  ...  1  Cor.  xii.  8-11),  or 

i  IF.  36  (italics  mine).  2  n.  32.  3  II.  22. 

300 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

from  the  Book  of  Genesis,  where  it  says :  Et  Spiritus  Dei  fovebat 
aquas.  For  to  what  other  purpose  could  the  Spirit  of  God  have 
cherished  and  made  fruitful  and  nourished  the  waters  (which  upon 
Erigeiia's  allegorical  interpretation  are  the  causae  primordiales) ,  than 
to  distribute  and  arrange,  according  to  the  distinctions  of  classes  and 
forms,  of  wholes  and  parts,  and  of  all  numbers,  that  reality  (the 
causae  primordiales)  which  in  the  Word  was  created  in  uniformity,, 
unity,  and  simplicity? 

The  causae  primordiales  which  are  one,  as  created  by  the  Father 
in  the  Word,  are,  then,  made  manifold  and  distributed  into  their 
effects  by  the  Holy  Ghost.  For  Erigena,  a  living  and  continuous  divine 
energy  is  thus  both  the  principle  of  unity  of  the  Ideas,  and  the  source 
of  that  expansive  power  and  creative  energy  by  which  they  proceed 
from  themselves  and  give  rise  to  the  orders  of  particular  being  which 
make  up  the  third  Form  of  Nature.  This  transition  from  the  Ideas 
to  the  things  of  the  present  world  had  been  a  difficulty  both  for  Plato 
and  for  Plotinus.  Plato,  as  we  have  seen,  worked  his  way  steadily 
toward  a  solution  of  it.  He  came  more  and  more  to  regard  the 
hierarchy  of  the  Ideas  not  so  much  as  a  universe  complete  in  itself, 
abiding  for  ever  in  static  perfection,  and  by  that  perfection  rebuking 
this  second  universe  in  which  we  live;  but  rather  as  the  order,  the 
rational  constitution,  of  the  one  universe  to  which  all  reality  belongs. 
And  this  he  could  do,  because  he  more  and  more  came  to  regard  the 
Ideas,  not  as  mere  forms  of  static  perfection,  but  as  creative  energies 
sharing  in  the  nature  of  that  supreme  principle  which  is  at  once  the 
source  of  their  reality  and  the  principle  of  their  organisation.  While 
Plotinus,  in  tracing  the  descent  from  the  vovs  through  the  world-soul 
to  the  world  of  particulars,  can  but  bring  up  the  same  logical  devices 
that  he  had  already  used  in  attempting  to  bridge  a  similar,  but 
profounder,  gulf — that  between  the  One  and  the  vovs.  But  for 
Erigena,  the  Christian  theology  of  the  Greeks  makes  possible  that 
which  to  the  pagan  theology  of  the  Greeks  was  not  possible.  The  self- 
manifesting  and  self-communicating  Father  pours  Himself  forth 
through  all  the  descending  stages  of  existence,  constituting  the  Ideas 
in  the  Son,  and  in  the  Holy  Ghost  distributing  them  into  their  effects. 

It  is  not  an  easy  task  to  reduce  any  aspect  of  Erigena's  thought  to 

301 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

cold  and  systematic  statement.  And  within  the  limits  of  the  present 
discussion  it  is  simply  not  possible  to  consider  the  details  of  the 
gigantic  cosmogony  which  he  works  out  in  dealing  with  the  third 
Form  of  Nature.  From  the  causae  primordiales — not  out  of  nothing 
—proceed  the  four  universal  elements.1  These  mediate  between  the 
purely  spiritual  primordial  causes  and  particular  bodies.2  So  that 
matter  is  viewed  as  arising  from  the  combination  of  incorporeal  exis 
tences.  For  qualities  and  quantities  which  in  themselves  are  incorpor 
eal,,  by  coming  together  bring  into  being  formless  matter,  which  by 
the  addition  of  incorporeal  forms  and  colours  takes  shape  in  diverse 
bodies  (literally,  "is  moved  into  diverse  bodies" — compare  Aris- 
totle'a  HirrjGis).3  Then  by  distinguishing  in  compounded  bodies, 
(1)  the  matter,  (2)  the  immanent  or  individual  form,  (3)  the 
essential  or  general  (and  therefore  separable)  form,  he  brings  forward 
what  is  really  Plato's  and  Aristotle's  problem  of  the  relation  of  form 
and  matter,  with  the  connected  problem  of  the  relation  of  essential  and 
contingent.4  Man,  again,  he  views  as  created  in  the  image  of  God,  and 
therefore  as  containing  within  himself  all  created  existences  from  the 
heavenly  to  the  animal — so  that  "  in  man  God  has  created  the  whole 
visible  and  invisible  creature."  "  Although  it  remains  to  this  day 
hidden,  how  far  the  first  estate  of  man  reaches,  since  his  transgression 
by  revolt  from  the  heavenly  light,  still  there  is  nothing  naturally 
present  in  the  celestial  essences  which  does  not  subsist  essentially  in 
man."  "  The  whole  sensible  world  is  created  in  him ;  no  part  of  it  can 
be  found,  whether  corporeal  or  incorporeal,  which  in  created  man  does 
not  subsist,  feel,  live,  and  become  incarnate."5 

With  the  details  of  this  part  of  Erigena's  system,  however, — and 
with  the  great  allegorical  exposition  by  which  he  brings  both  this  and 
other  parts  of  his  system  out  of  the  opening  chapters  of  Genesis — it  is 
impossible  here  to  deal.  But  although  we  cannot  go  into  the  details, 
yet  if  we  are  to  understand  Erigena  at  all,  we  must  consider  the 
broad  movement  of  thought,  and  the  chief  logical  motives,  in  this  part 

1  III.  14. 

2  III.  26.    Compare  the  phrase  in  III.  27.     "...    the  threefold  creation  of  the  world, 
namely,  in  its  grounds  (rationibus),  its  universal  elements,  its  particular  and  compounded 
bodies." 

3  III.  14.  4  HI.  27.  ?>  IV.  7  seq. 

302 


EBIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

of  his  account  of  the  world.  For  what  it  contains  is  precisely  that 
dualism  which  we  have  already  seen  in  Plato  and  Aristotle,  and  which 
haunts  theology  to  this  day;  the  dualism  that  arises  from  the  sense, 
on  the  one  side,  of  the  perfection  of  God  as  the  source  of  the  world; 
on  the  other  side,  of  the  imperfection  of  the  world  which  has  come 
from  that  God. 

That  dualism  may  be  said  to  be  absolutely  inevitable  for  all 
affirmative  theology  which  is  not  able  to  view  the  process  of  the  world 
and  of  man's  spiritual  history,  from  the  point  of  view  of  development 
or  evolution.  And  this  conception  and  point  of  view,  it  should  be 
understood,  is  not  forced  upon  theology  from  the  outside.  It  is  called 
for  from  within.^-  For  anything  that  can  be  called  affirmative  theology 
at  all,  must  view  God  as  a  self -communicating  being;  as  a  being 
whose  nature  it  is  to  impart  his  nature.  And  that  means  that  God 
must  give  rise  to  spiritual  beings  of  a  nature  kindred  to  His  own,  and 
must  impart  Himself  to  them.  But  such  impartation  on  God's  part 
means  struggle  on  their  part.  For  unless  in  some  very  real  sense 
they  earn  their  own  life  and  achieve  their  own  perfection — unless,  in 
one  word,  they  "  have  life  in  themselves  " — they  cannot  be  regarded 
as  beings  to  whom  God  imparts  Himself.  They  would  have  simply 
a  life  and  a  perfection  laid  upon  them  from  the  outside;  would  have 
no  life  or  perfection  of  their  own.  They  would,  in  fact,  in  their 
unsuffering  and  untormented  innocence,  be  (morally,  if  not  meta 
physically)  modes  of  the  divine  substance,  rather  than  spirits  made  in 
the  likeness  of  God — spirits  in  whom  God  reproduces  Himself,  and  to 
whom,  therefore,  and  only  therefore,  He  can  impart  Himself.  So 
that,  as  we  have  already  seen,1  affirmative  theology  must  view  God  in 
creation  as  making  the  actual,  empirical  beginning  with  something 
less  than  His  own  eternal  perfection,  and  from  that  beginning  leading 
created  beings  onward  through  a  process  of  development,  which 
from  God's  side  may  be  described  as  an  ever-increasing  impartation 
of  Himself,  but  from  man's  side  as  a  desperate  struggle  upward 
through  evil.  But  Plato  and  Aristotle — all  the  more  remarkably  in 
Aristotle's  case  because  he  does  see  evolution  in  nature — cannot  admit 
such  a  view.  Any  result  of  the  divine  activity,  any  creation  of  God, 

i  Supra,  p.  82  seq.    Cf.  p.  242  seg.  and  p.  258. 
303 


EEIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

they  instinctively  feel,  must  have  eternally  in  it  the  absolute  and  final 
perfection  of  God;  if  a  creation-theory  can  be  admitted  at  all,  it 
must  view  the  perfect  and  timeless  maker  as  making  a  timelessly  per 
fect  work.  But  the  world  actually  present  to  us  is  an  order  of  becom 
ing,  and  is  full  of  imperfection.  Hence  Plato  is  forced  to  a  dualism 
(the  admission  of  a  co-eternal  impeding  principle  in  creation),  which 
Aristotle  hardens  and  makes  more  decisive.  And  for  Erigena  in  his 
affirmative  theology,  this  situation  is  intensified  and  made  most  aculc. 
For  he  sees  this  present  world  as  intimately  in  connexion  with  God; 
in  fact,  as  he  emphatically  puts  it,  what  God  creates  in  the  second 
and  third  Form  of  Nature  is  Himself;  in  those  Forms,  God 
"  becomes,"  God  "  is  created."  Hence,  for  Erigena,  if  one  may  so 
express  it,  God  in  the  world  and  the  evil  in  the  world  stand  directly 
face  to  face,  and  the  problem  that  troubled  Plato  and  Aristotle  is 
intensified  to  the  utmost. 

We  must  briefly  consider  the  presence  in  Erigena  of  each  of  the 
two  insights  whose  opposition  thus  constitutes  the  ultimate — and  des 
perate — problem  of  theology  and  philosophy.  It  is  understood,  of 
course,  that  in  doing  so  we  are  confining  ourselves  to  Erigena's 
affirmative  theology;  for  the  negative  theologian,  when  he  has 
reached  his  goal,  has  delivered  himself  even  from  this  problem;  he 
has  but  to  be  still,  having  come  to  his  rest  in  God. 

First,  Erigena  never  wavers  from  the  height  of  his  assertion  of 
the  unity,  and  eternity,  and  divinity,  of  Nature  through  all  its  Forms. 
This  does  not  mean  that  he  deifies  the  rocks  and  trees.  It  means  that 
for  him  God  is  all  in  all ;  it  means  that  he  has  penetrated  beyond  the 
appearance  of  the  things  of  the  earth  to  their  reality,  and  has  found 
that  reality  to  be  God.  In  all  creation  God  creates  Himself;  in  all 
becoming  it  is  God  that  becomes.  All  the  four  Forms  of  Nature  are 
the  procession  of  God,  from  Himself,  through  Himself,  to  Himself. 
"...  To  God  there  is  nothing  future,  for  He  includes  (con- 
dudat)  within  Himself  all  times  together  with  their  content,  and  is 
the  beginning,  the  middle,  and  the  end,  the  extent  and  course  and 
return  of  all  things."  "Thou  compellest  us  now  to  confess,"  the 
Scholar  presently  replies,  "  that  God  is  all — all  that  is  said  to  be 
eternal,  all  that  is  said  to  have  become.  For  if  the  divine  will  and 

304 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

the  divine  vision  are  essential  and  eternal,  and,  for  God,  being, 
willing,  and  seeing,  are  not  different  things,  but  one  thing,  and  that 
superessential;  if,  furthermore,  all  that  makes  up  the  object  of  his 
willing  and  seeing  can  reasonably  be  understood  as  nothing  other 
than  Himself,  since  a  simple  nature  can  admit  in  itself  nothing 
which  it  itself  is  not:  then  beyond  all  dispute  no  other  conclusion 
remains  than  to  confess  that  the  one  God  is  all  in  all.  ...  If  the 
nature  of  the  divine  Goodness,"  the  Scholar  farther  admits,  "  is 
distinct  from  that  which  God  saw  as  something  destined  to  become, 
and  made, — saw  thus,  and  made,  in  Himself — then  the  simplicity  of 
the  divine  nature  is  rent  apart,  if  an  Other  is  understood  in  it  which 
is  not  itself.  But  this  is  absolutely  impossible.  And  if  the  divine 
nature  is  not  distinct  from  that  which  it  saw  in  itself  as  something 
to  be  made;  if  it  is,  rather,  one  and  the  same  divine  nature,  whose 
simplicity  is  inviolable,  and  whose  unity  is  indivisible;  then  with 
certainty  it  follows  that  God  is  everywhere  all,  and  wholly  in  every 
thing,  at  once  the  maker  and  that  which  is  made,  the  seer  and  that 
which  is  seen,  at  once  the  time  and  place  and  essence  and  substance 
and  accidents  of  all  things;  in  short,  is  everything  which  truly  is  or 
is  not;  superessential  in  the  essences,  supersubstantial  in  the  substances, 
high  above  every  creature  as  Creator,  and  within  every  creature  as 
created  [in  the  creature  God  creates  Himself],  and  underneath  every 
creature  as  subsistent  [or,  as  substratum] ,  beginning  to  be  from  Him 
self,  moving  Himself  through  Himself,  and  moved  to  Himself,  and 
resting  in  Himself,  made  infinitely  manifold  in  Himself  through 
genera  and  species,  without  any  loss  of  the  simplicity  of  His  nature, 
and  calling  back  into  Himself  the  infinity  of  His  manifoldness.  For 
in  Him  all  things  are  one."  "  Now  I  see/'  is  the  Master's  answer, 
"  that  in  place  of  thy  doubts  clear  insight  has  come,  and  that  thou 
wilt  no  longer  hesitate  to  confess  that  all  things  are  at  once  '  become ' 
and  eternal  (et  facta  et  eterna),  and  that  everything  which  is  seen 
truly  to  subsist  in  them  is  nothing  other  than  the  ineffable  nature 
of  the  divine  Goodness."  .  .  .  "The  conclusion  is,  that  in  all 
things,  it  [the  divine  nature]  alone  truly  and  properly  is;  and 
nothing  which  is  not  that  nature  truly  properly  is.  .  .  .  So  that 
we  ought  not  to  regard  God  and  the  creature  as  two  existences  distinct 

•21  305 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

from  each  other;  rather  they  are  one  and  the  same.  For  the  creature 
subsists  in  God,  and  God  in  wonderful  and  ineffable  wise  is  created 
in  the  creature;  revealing  Himself;  the  invisible  making  Himself 
visible,  the  incomprehensible  making  Himself  comprehensible,  the 
hidden,  open,  the  unknown,  known;  the  God  above  form  and  appear 
ance  making  Himself  beautiful  in  form,  gracious  in  appearance;  the 
superessential  making  Himself  essential,  the  supernatural,  natural, 
the  simple,  complex;  the  God  exalted  above  accidental  qualities  mak 
ing  Himself  subject  to  such  qualities,  and  becoming  such  a  quality; 
the  infinite  making  Himself  finite,  the  uncircumscribed,  circum 
scribed,  the  supertemporal,  temporal,  the  superlocal,  local ;  the  Creator 
of  all  being  created  in  all,  and  the  Maker  of  all  made  in  all;  so  that 
the  eternal  begins  to  be,  and  the  immutable  is  changed  into  all 
(immobilis  movetur  in  omnia)  and  in  all  things  becomes  all.  And 
this  I  say,  not  with  reference  to  the  incarnation  of  the  Word,  and  His 
becoming  man,  but  with  reference  to  the  ineffable  condescension  of 
the  Supreme  Goodness,  which  is  Unity  and  Trinity,  into  the  things 
which  are,  in  order  that  they  may  be,  nay,  in  order  that  it  may  be 
itself  in  all  things  from  the  highest  to  the  lowest,  always  eternal, 
always  ( become/  eternal  of  itself,  '  become '  in  itself ;  while  eternal, 
not  ceasing  to  be  become ;  while  become,  not  ceasing  to  be  eternal ;  and 
making  itself  of  itself.  For  it  needs  not  some  other  matter,  which 
is  not  itself,  in  order  therein  to  make  itself;  else  would  it  seem  pow 
erless,  and  imperfect  in  itself,  if  from  some  other  where  it  received 
aid  for  its  appearance  and  perfection.  From  Himself,  then,  God 
received  the  occasions  to  His  theophanies — which  is  to  say,  divine 
appearances — for  '  of  Him,  and  through  Him,  in  Him,  and  to  Him, 
are  all  things/  And  therefore  the  matter  itself,  of  which  the  world 
is  said  to  have  been  made,  is  from  Him  and  in  Him;  and  He  is  in 
it  so  far  as  it  is  regarded  as  having  existence."1 

So  that  all  things  are  divine  and  are  a  to  turn  simul  in  God.  That 
of  which  God  made  the  world  He  took  no  other  where  than  from  Him 
self,  and  "  neither  sought  spaces  outside  of  Himself,  in  which  to  create, 
nor  paid  regard  to  times,  in  order  in  their  intervals  to  complete  His 
work,  but  made  all  things  in  Himself;  since  He  is  the  space  of  all 

i  III.  17. 

306 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

things,  and  the  time  of  times,  and  the  age  of  ages,  accomplishing 
all  things  together  and  making  all  things  in  the  twinkling  of  an  eye. 
For  both  those  things  which  in  the  course  of  the  ages  have  come  to 
birth,  and  those  that  even  now  are  coming  to  birth,  and  those  whose 
birth  is  still  to  come,  are  all  together  and  at  once  made  in  Him,  in 
whom  past  and  present  and  future  are  all  together,  and  all  at  once, 
and  all  one."1  "  God  saw,  then,  that  it  was  good,  that  is  to  say,  God 
saw  Himself  in  all  things  as  the  good.  For  God  saw  nothing  but! 
Himself,  because  outside  of  Him  there  is  nothing,  and  all  that  is  in 
Him  is  Himself,  and  his  vision  of  Himself  is  simple  and  has  its  form 
from  none  other  than  Himself."2 

But  over  against  this  vision  of  the  theologian  to  whom  God  is  all 
and  in  all,  and  all  cognisable  things  theophanies,  stands  the  life  of 
the  present  world.  And  as  Erigena  looks  upon  it,  the  problem  is 
forced  upon  him  which  has  been  forced  upon  all  the  greater  theo 
logians  from  Plato  downward :  How — and  why — has  evil  come  to  have 
a  place  in  a  world  whose  source  is  altogether  good?  Erigena  sees — 
what  any  one  who  deserves  the  name  of  theologian  must  see — that  the 
werld  is  one  as  coming  from  one  source;  and  that,  therefore,  in  ulti-  y^ 
mate  analysis,  all  the  elements  or  factors  of  the  world  have  their1 
ground  in  one  character  and  subserve  one  purpose.  But,  then,  what 
account  can  one  give  of  the  place  of  evil  in  such  a  world?  And  if 
you  can  give  no  account — if  you  cannot  see  even  the  beginning  or 
promise  of  an  explanation — what  right  have  you  to  retain  your  funda 
mental  conception  of  the  unity  of  all  existence? — if  you  thus  are 
really  a  Manicha?an,  what  right,  for  instance,  have  you  to  call  your 
self  a  Theist? 

We  must  distinguish,  of  course,  between  an  empirical  account 
of  the  origin  of  evil  and  a  metaphysical  account.  The  empirical 
account  simply  describes  as  a  matter  of  fact  how  evil  comes  to  be; 
the  metaphysical  seeks  for  the  ground  of  evil,  where  all  things  must 
somehow  have  their  ground — in  ultimate  eternity.  An  empirical 
account  Erigena  easily  gives:  evil  arises  from  "perverse  motions  of 
the  free  will."3  In  modern  language,  evil  is  the  correlate  of  man's 
freedom.  And  when  it  is  recognised  that  freedom  on  the  part  of  man 

i  III.  27.  2  HI.  28.  3  See,  e.g.,  IV.  5. 

307 


EBIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

is  necessary  to  any  genuine  self-communication  on  the  part  of  God, 
the  way  is  prepared  for  the  metaphysical  account  which  has  already 
been  referred  to,1  and  which,  grave  as  are  its  difficulties,,  is  at  least 
free  from  self-contradiction — one  part  of  it  does  not  deny  the  other 
part. 

But  Erigena  does  not  advance  to  this  point  of  view ;  though  there 
are  hints  of  it  in  him2 — as,  indeed,  there  arc  in  him  hints  of  nearly 
everything  in  philosophy.  On  the  contrary,  he  breaks  at  last  that  to 
which  he  so  passionately  held,  the  belief  in  the  inviolable  unity  of  all 
existence.  He  falls  into  a  dualism  resembling,  not  in  expression, 
indeed,  but  in  logical  motive,  that  of  Plato  and  Aristotle.  Evil 
becomes  to  him  what  the  "  Necessity  "  of  the  Timaeus  is  to  Plato,  or 
contingency  to  Aristotle — virtually  a  co-eternal  principle  which  inter 
feres  with  the  perfection  of  the  created  world.  The  very  intensity  of 
his  idea  of  unity  coupled  with  his  lack  of  clearly-possessed  organic 
categories,  drives  him  into  the  following  position. —  (1)  Evil,  alike 
in  its  origin  and  in  its  being,  lies  outside  of  (C  Nature."  "  God,  then, 
does  not  know  evil.  For  if  He  knew  evil,  evil  would  necessarily  be  in 
the  nature  of  things.  For  the  divine  knowledge  is  the  cause  of  all 
things  which  are.  .  .  .  The  cause  of  the  essence  of  these  things  is 
the  divine  knowledge,  and,  therefore,  if  God  knew  evil,  then  evil  would 
be  perceived  substantially  in  something;  evil  would  participate  in  the 
good,  and  thus  from  strength  and  goodness  defect  and  evil  would 
proceed.  But  that  this  is  impossible,  true  wisdom  teaches."3  (2)  How 
anything  which  thus  has  no  place  in  Nature,  which,  indeed,  contradicts 

1  Supra,  p.  242  seq.;  p.  258  ;  p.  303.    Cf.  p.  82  seg. 

2  One  of  the  >e— which  may  be  said  to  present  the  theory  in  question  in  its  static  form 
(the  form.  Stoic  and  Leibnizian,  which  views  evil  as  contributing  to  good,  not  as  the 
negative  factor  involved  in  Development,  but  rather  as  the  imperfection  which  presents 
itself  when  you  'ook  at  the  single  finite  individual  instead  of  at  the  whole)— is  specially 
striking:  "How,"  an  objector  is  imagined  to  say,  "can  God,  exalted  high  over  a1],  invis 
ible,  incorporeal,  incorruptible,  descend  from  Himself;  and  create  Himself  in  all  things, 
in  order  to  be  all  in  all ;  and,  in  His  forthgoing.  advance  to  the  last  visible  hatefulnesses 
and  corruptions,  to  the  meanest  forms  and  species,  of  this  world,  in  order  to  be  in  these, 
if  He  is  all  in  all?"    "He,"ru'  s  the  answer,  "who  so  speaks,  knows  not  that  in  the  total 
universe  of  the  creature  there  can  be  nothing  hateful,  that  it  no  evil  can  mar,  that  it  by 
no  error  can  be  deceived  or  led  astray.    For  what  concerns  only  a  part,  Gnd  does  not 
permit  to  become  in  the  whole,  since,  upon  a  view  of  the  whole,  neither  is  [what  had 
seemed]  hatefulness  hateful,  nor  does  any  evil  injure,  nor  any  error  mislead."    (III.  20.) 

3  1.28. 

308 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

and  opposes  Nature,  could  come  into  existence  at  all — for,  of  course, 
there  are  no  sources  outside  of  Nature — is  a  "mystery."  Yet  even 
here  Erigena  has  a  glimpse  of  a  solution;  a  glimpse  to  which  only  a 
doctrine  of  development  as  a  divine  method  could  do  justice.  "  Every 
thing  which  in  '  natural '  wise  is  created  in  man,  remains  of  necessity 
eternally  inviolate  and  uncorrupted.  .  .  .  The  rational  and  intel 
lectual  nature,  although  it  was  not  willingly  deceived,  yet  could  be 
beguiled,  especially  since  it  had  not  yet  received  the  perfection  of  the 
form  which — destined  as  that  nature  was  to  a  course  of  transformation 
ending  in  theosis,  that  is  to  say,  deification — it  was  to  have  received 
through  the  merit  of  obedience  (perfectionem  .  .  .  quam  merito 
obedientiae  esset  acceptura  in  theosin,  deificationem  dico,  transfor- 
manda)  .'J1  (3)  Evil,  once  it  had  thus  by  perverse  motions  of  the  will 
arisen,  explains  the  dividedness  and  imperfection  of  the  third  Form  of 
Nature.  A  single  passage  of  many  will  make  Erigena's  view  clear. 
"  For,  as  reason  teaches,  this  would  not  have  fallen  apart  into  its 
manifold  sensible  species,  and  into  the  motley  diversity  of  its  parts,  if 
God  had  not  foreseen  the  fall  and  ruin  of  the  first  man,  who  forsook 
the  unity  of  his  nature;  to  the  end  that  man — at  least  after  his  fall 
from  the  spiritual  realm  to  the  corporeal,  from  the  eternal  to  the 
temporal,  from  the  incorruptible  to  the  perishable,  from  the  highest 
to  the  lowest,  from  the  spiritual  man  to  an  animal,  from  a  simple 
nature  to  the  distinction  of  the  sexes,  from  angelic  dignity  and  multi 
plication  to  the  shame  of  the  birth  of  our  corruptible  bodies — being 
admonished  by  a  penalty  so  dire,  might  come  to  recognise  his  pitiable 
ruin,  and  seek  to  return  to  the  condition  of  his  pristine  dignity  by 
repentance  and  the  putting  off  of  his  pride  and  by  the  fulfilment  of 
the  divine  laws  which  he  had  transgressed.  For  it  cannot  be  believed 
that  the  most  divine  charity  of  the  Creator  has  thrust  sinful  man  down 
into  this  world  as  if  through  some  movement  of  wrath  or  desire  of 
vengeance;  since  true  reason  shows  us  that  the  divine  Goodness  is 
free  from  these  non-essential  qualities  (his  accidentibus] .  Rather  it 
can  have  happened  only  in  consequence  of  an  ineffable  principle  and 
of  mercy  incomprehensible;  to  the  end  that  man — though  by  the 
choice  of  his  free  will  he  had  refused  to  maintain  himself  in  the 

i  TV.  o. 

309 


EBIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

dignity  of  his  nature — taught  by  punishment,  should  seek  the  grace 
of  his  Creator;  and,  obeying  by  the  help  of  that  grace  the  divine 
commands  which  earlier  he  had  neglected  out  of  pride,  careful  and 
cautious  and  mindful  of  his  earlier  negligence  and  of  his  proud 
humiliating  fall,  should  turn  back  toward  his  ancient  state,  from 
which — preserved  by  grace  and  by  the  free  choice  of  his  own  will — he 
should  not  fall  again,  nor  wish  to  fall,  nor  be  able  to  fall."1 

Such,  then,  is  Erigena7  s  account  of  the  forthgoing  of  the  divina 
bonitas,  and  of  the  Forms  of  Nature  which  thus  arise:  the  second 
Form,  the  world  of  Ideas,  a  system  of  perfect  types  and  perfect 
energies ;  the  third  Form,  our  present  world,  the  result  partly  of  the 
farther  procession  of  the  divine  goodness,  partly  of  man's  sin.  With 
this,  we  have  to  turn  to  the  last  of  the*  Forms  of  Nature,  that  in  which 
all  things  return  to  their  source  in  God.  In  the  light  of  what  we  have 
just  seen,  this  will  be  not  only  the  natural  return  of  all  things  to  their 
source,  but  also  their  redemption  from  evil.  And  if  Erigena  is  to  be 
understood,  special  attention  must  be  given  to  this  part  of  his  thought. 
Just  as  we  do  not  understand  Dante  at  all  if  we  read  only  the 
Inferno — because  "it  is  interesting,  while  no  person  can  live  in  the 
white  light  of  the  Paradiso  " — so  we  shall  not  understand  Erigena  at 
all,  nor  indeed  any  mediasval  theologian,  unless  we  walk  with  him  while 
he  unfolds  his  highest  hope  and  ultimate  vision. 

But  before  turning  to  this  we  must  stop  for  a  moment  upon  an 
aspect  of  Erigena's  thought,  which  is  very  important,  but  which  the 
course  of  the  discussion  so  far  has  given  us  no  opportunity  to  bring 
forward.  This  is  what  we  may  call  his  Idealism.  The  whole  of  that 
reality  about  which  it  is  possible  for  science  or  philosophy  to  make 
affirmations  is,  he  sees,  of  the  nature  of  thought.  And  to  this  Idealism 
he  comes  from  both  sides :  from  the  side  of  the  material  order ;  from 
the  side  of  God.  In  the  first  Book,  in  dealing  with  the  inapplicability 
of  the  ten  categories  to  God,  he  works  out  a  sort  of  "  immaterialism  " ; 
he  reduces  the  corporeal  to  the  incorporeal.  Matter  is  a  combination 
of  incorporeal  qualities  and  quantities.  And  the  form  which  holds  it 
together  is  incorporeal.  And  this  immaterialism  passes  over  into 

i  II.  12. 

310 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

express  Idealism  when  it  is  said  that  space  is  arrangement  or  order, 
and  therefore  subsists  only  in  the  mind ;  space  is  a  definition,  and  its 
determinations  must  be  the  activity  of  a  rational  and  thinking  nature ; 
space  is  something  thought  in  the  soul,  and  is  therefore  incorporeal. 
Hence,  indeed,  it  is,  as  Gregory  of  Nyssa  says,  that  from  a  God  whose 
nature  is  that  of  thought  or  spirit,  a  "material"  world  can  come.1 
While  from  the  side  of  God,  he  equally  maintains  that  all  created 
existence  is  of  the  nature  of  thought.  "  God,"  he  says,  in  dealing  with 
the  problem  of  evil,  "  does  not  know  that  which  is,  because  it  subsists ; 
but  it  subsists  because  God  knows  it.  The  cause  of  the  essence  of  that 
which  is,  is  the  divine  knowledge."2  "  The  knowledge  of  the  saints  in 
the  Wisdom  of  the  Father,"  he  says  again,  "  is  the  creation  of  them. 
For  the  perception  in  God  of  all  things  is  the  essence  of  all  things."3 
In  a  word,  God's  knowledge  of  an  existence  is  that  existence.  Or,  to 
put  the  same  conception  into  more  modern  terms,  the  objective  reality 
of  anything  means  its  presence  in  the  divine  mind.  It  will,  of  course, 
be  understood  that  this  does  not  necessarily  deny  selfhood — real 
individuality  or  the  germ  of  it — to  created  beings;  and,  therefore,  is 
not  necessarily  Pantheism. 

Furthermore,  Erigena  in  his  affirmative  theology  is  not  only  an 
Idealist  in  the  sense  of  asserting  that  all  reality  which  science  or 
philosophy  can  investigate  is  of  the  nature  of  thought  or  spirit.  He 
really  possesses  also  the  true  point  of  departure  of  Idealism:  he  sees 
that  spirit  as  it  is  in  man  is  an  active  principle  of  synthesis.  He 
delights  to  pourtray  the  human  soul  as  not  imprisoned  in  space,  nor 
compelled  to  "  reach  out  into  space,"  but  as  having — to  use  modern 
language — a  synthetic  activity  which  is  above  the  dividedness  of  space 
and  time,  receiving  at  one  and  the  same  time,  and  into  one  and  the 
same  experience,  the  most  manifold  kinds  of  sensation,  retaining  these 
in  memory,  arranging  and  judging  them.4  Hence,  when  he  goes  on 
with  equal  intensity  to  describe  the  soul  as  simplex,  free  from  all  union 
or  composition  of  distinct  parts,  he  can  only  be  understood  as  having 
a  conception  of  the  soul  which  he  is  not  able  clearly  to  express — the 
conception  of  it  as  a  diversity-in-unity,  a  principle  and  activity  of 
synthesis.  The  very  reason  which  he  gives  in  insisting  upon  its 

1  I.  27-61.  2  II.  28.  s  II.  20.  4  III.  30. 

311 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

simplicity  shows  this.  It  is  a  simplex,  free  from  all  composition  of 
distinct  parts,  he  says,  because  "  in  itself  it  is  in  its  wholeness  every 
where  throughout  the  whole.  It  is  the  whole  life,  the  whole  under 
standing,  the  whole  reason,  the  whole  of  sense,  the  whole  memory, 
and,  as  this  whole,  it  animates,  nourishes,  maintains  and  increases  the 
body.  As  the  whole  soul,  it,  in  all  the  senses,  perceives  the  forms  of 
sensible  things.  As  the  whole  soul,  it  deals  with,  distinguishes,  com 
bines,  separates — going  far  beyond  every  bodily  sense — the  nature  and 
reason  of  the  sensible  things  themselves.  As  the  whole  soul — beyond 
and  above  every  creature,  and  above  itself  as  a  being  included  in  the 
world  of  creatures — it  circles  in  intelligible  and  eternal  motion  about 
its  Creator,  becoming  purified  of  all  vices  and  imaginations."  And,  as 
Erigena  goes  on,  in  this  very  simplicity,  it  receives  distinctions  and 
distinct  names  according  to  its  activities.  In  its  motion  about  the 
divine  essence  it  is  Mind  and  Soul  and  Understanding.  In  dealing 
with  the  natures  and  causes  of  created  things  it  is  Keason.  In 
receiving  sensuous  images,  it  is  Sense.  As  animating  the  body,  it  is 
the  Vital  Principle.  But  in  all  these  activities  it  is  everywhere  the 
whole  soul.1  The  same  insight  appears  in  Erigena's  view  of  the  soul 
as  a  microcosm,  which  we  shall  have  to  consider  in  another  connexion. 
Thus,  then,  Idealism  is  present  in  the  De  Divisione  Naturae; 
Erigena  has  both  its  true  point  of  departure  and  its  specific  insights. 
But  neither  the  age  that  he  lived  in,  nor  the  history  that  lay  behind 
him,  nor  his  equipment  of  categories,  permitted  the  Idealism  in  him 
to  come  fully  to  its  right.  With  his  inheritance  of  the  Christian 
theology  of  the  Greeks,  he  stood  between  two  worlds,  the  one  of  which 
had  spoken  in  Plotinus  and  Proclus,  the  other  of  which  was  to  speak 
in  Hegel.  To  both  of  those  worlds  his  heart  was  given;  and  the 
result  was  that  Idealism  was  present  in  him  not  as  expressing  his 
highest  insight  and  last  conviction,  but  simply  as  one  stage  in  that 
desperate  journey  of  the  intellect  which  is  set  for  any  man  who  is  a 
Mystic,  and  yet  cannot  plainly  and  flatly  deny  the  reality  of  the 
present  world. 

We  have  to  return,  then,  to  the  subject  already    before  us — the 

i  IV.  5.     Cf.  11. 
312 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

fourth  Form  of  Nature.  It  would  seem  at  first  sight  as  if  Erigena's 
work  of  explaining  the  world  were  already  done,  when  he  had  given 
his  account  of  original  reality  and  of  the  derivation  of  our  present 
world  from  it.  But  we  have  already  seen  that  his  instinct  for  unity 
drives  him  farther.  The  world  has  come  from  one  source,  but  it  is 
nevertheless  not  one.  It  is  beset  by  dividedness ;  and  by  dividedness  of 
a  particularly  unforgivable  kind — sensuous  manifoldness,  diversity  in 
space  and  time.  And  worse  still,  it  is  torn  apart  by  the  dualism  of 
good  and  evil.  Futhermore,  to  the  discontent  of  the  philosophic  and 
moral  mind  there  is  added  the  discontent  of  the  specifically  religious 
mind :  God  must  be  all  in  all,  and  all  things  that  have  proceeded  from 
Him  must  return  to  Him. 

So,  then,  we  come  to  a  fourth  Form  of  Nature,  which  neither  is 
created  nor  creates,  but  in  which  all  things  rest  eternally  in  their  home 
and  unity  in  God.  In  attempting  to  deal  with  this,  we  must  first 
notice  the  general  principle  which  guides  Erigena  in  this  part  of  his 
work,  and  must  then  indicate  very  briefly  the  main  steps  in  the  return 
of  all  things  from  their  multiplicity  and  dividedness  in  the  third  Form 
to  their  rest  in  the  fourth. 

To  Erigena  it  is  a  general  principle  of  Nature  that  things  return 
to  their  beginnings.  The  source  from  which  they  proceed  is  also  their 
goal.  This  is  seen  even  in  corporeal  things;  and  as  so  seen,  it 
mystically  intimates  to  us  (for  "there  is,  in  my  opinion,  nothing 
among  visible  and  corporeal  things  which  is  not  a  sign  of  something 
incorporeal  and  intelligible  ")  "  the  return  of  our  nature  to  the  source 
whence  it  originated,  and  in  which  and  through  which  it  moves,  and 
to  which  it  always  strives  to  return.  Universally  in  all  men,  whether 
they  be  perfect  or  imperfect,  pure  or  defiled,  made  new  by  knowledge 
of  the  truth  in  Christ  or  cleaving  to  the  old  man  in  the  darkness  of 
ignorance,  lives  one  and  the  same  natural  desire  for  being,  and  well- 
being,  and  abiding  being,  or,  as  St.  Augustine  briefly  expresses  it,  the 
desire  to  live  happily  and  avoid  misery.1  But  this  impulse  after  living 
happily  and  having  substantial  existence  is  from  Him  who  is  eternal 
and  is  good  and  is  immanent  in  all  things.  And  if  every  natural 
motion,  of  necessity  does  not  cease  nor  rest,  until  it  has  reached  the 

i  Compare  the  conatus  in  sito  esse  perscverandi  of  Spinoza. 
313 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

goal  toward  which  it  struggles,  what  can  avail  to  hinder  or  restrain 
or  bring  to  a  stand  the  necessary  movement  of  human  nature,  so  that  it 
shall  not  be  able  to  reach  that  for  which  it  naturally  strives?"  And 
even,  "  if  godlike  Nature  has  somehow  through  unlikeness  become 
remote  from  its  source,  it  strives  always  to  return  thither,  in  order  to 
attain  again  to  the  likeness  which  it  had  marred. ""*• 

This  principle  itself  is  made  possible  for  Erigena  by  the  fact  that 
it  is  really  one  and  the  same  nature  which  is  present  in  the  first, 
second,  and  third  Forms.  In  the  first  Form,  that  one  Nature  is  viewed 
as  the  beginning  and  cause  of  all;  since  it  has  nothing  preceding  it 
which  could  stand  to  it  as  cause  or  beginning,  it  is  called  "  Nature 
creating  and  not  created."  Then,  in  the  second  Form,  where  it  is 
"both  created  and  creating,"  it  is  the  same  Nature.  For  the 
primordial  causes  are  that  Nature  "  creating  itself "  and  so  going 
forth  in  theophanies.  And  then  in  those  theophanies  it  still  farther 
proceeds  from,  or  unfolds,  itself,  coming  forth  from  the  most  concealed 
limits  of  its  nature,  in  which  it  is  unknown  even  to  itself,  that  is  to 
say,  recognises  itself  in  no  being  because  it  is  unconditioned  and  super 
natural  and  superessential  and  above  everything  that  can  be  thought 
or  not  thought.  When  it  thus  descends  into  the  principles  or  original 
grounds  of  things — into  the  causae  primordiales — and,  as  it  were, 
creates  itself,  it  begins  to  be  in  particular  and  definite  forms.  Then, 
further,  it  has  to  be  considered  in  the  last  effects  of  the  primordial 
causes,  wherein  it  is  rightly  viewed  simply  as  a  nature  which  "  is 
created,  but  does  not  create."  In  these  effects  it  comes  to  the  end  of 
its  forthgoing  and  manifestation — its  self-externalisation,  as  a  modern 
terminology  would  have  it.  Just  on  this  account,  every  corporeal  and 
visible  creature  given  to  our  senses  "  is  wont  in  the  Scriptures  not 
unjustly  to  be  called  the  last  trace  of  the  divine  nature  (extremum 
divinae  naturae  vestigium)"  This  trace  "it  is  vouchsafed  to  even- 
contemplative  mind  to  gain  sight  of,  when,  like  another  Moses,  it 
ascends  the  height  of  the  mount  of  vision;  although,  indeed,  it  can 
scarcely  be  distinguished  clearly  (ad  purum)  even  by  the  spirits  of 
the  wise;  for  the  smoke  of  earthly  imaginations,  and  the  tumult  of 
changeable  things,  and  the  gleaming  illusion  of  the  things  that 

i  v.  3. 
314 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

suddenly  are  born  and  pass  suddenly  from  us,  stand  as  hindrances 
in  the  way.  Only  very  few — those  that  from  earthly  thoughts 
wholly  have  set  themselves  free,  and  by  virtue  and  knowledge  are 
purified — attain  unto  it,  to  know  God  in  these  visible  creatures:"1 
as,  for  instance,  the  patriarch  Abraham  did,  when,  guided  by 
the  law  of  nature,  he  recognised  the  Creator  from  the  revolution 
of  the  stars;  and  other  holy  Fathers  before  the  written  kw, 
and  in  the  law — as  Moses  in  the  bush  and  upon  the  mountain- 
peak.  But,  in  addition  to  these  three  Forms,  there  is  still  another 
way  in  which  the  one  Nature  must  be  viewed :  "  When  we  recognise 
this  same  divine  nature  as  the  goal  of  all,  beyond  which  there  is 
nothing,  and  in  which  all  things  eternally  subsist  and  in  their 
universality  are  God,  then  we  rightly  call  it  neither  created  nor 
creating.  Not  created,  because  it  is  created  of  no  one;  not  creative, 
because  it  ceases  to  create  when  all  things  are  transformed  back  into 
their  original  grounds  (wherein  they  will  remain  eternally  and  do 
remain)  and  cease  to  be  known  by  the  name  creature.  For  God  will 
be  all  in  all,  and  every  creature,  transformed  into  God,  will  enter  into 
shadow,  as  the  stars  at  the  rising  of  the  sun.  Seest  thou  not,  then, 
upon  what  ground  one  and  the  same  nature,  namely,  the  divine,  can 
be  called  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  beginning  not  created,  but 
creating,  but  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  end  or  goal  neither  created 
nor  creating?"2  In  fact,  it  might  almost  be  said  that  Erigena's 
distinction  of  the  four  Forms  of  Nature  is  a  device  of  exposition,  a 
device  for  the  convenient  setting  forth  of  his  view  of  the  one  system 
of  the  one  universe.  The  first  and  fourth  Forms  express  the  unity,  the 

1  Compare  the  following  from  II.  18 :  "  The  first  causes,  then,  both  make  their  way 
(proveniunt)  into  the  things  of  which  they  are  the  causes,  and  do  not  forsake  their  source 
or  beginning  (principium),i.e.,  the  Wisdom  of  the  Father,  in  which  they  have  come  to  be, 
and — remaining,  so  to  speak,  in  themselves  invisible,  hidden  for  ever  in  the  darkness  of 
their  splendour,  but  in  their  effects  brought  forward  as  it  were  to  the  light  of  knowledge 
—appear  without  ceasing."    Or  the  following  from  the  Scholar  in  V.  24  :  "  Far  be  it  from 
the  hearts  of  the  faithful  to  think  that  everything  which  has  come  to  be  in  the  Word  of 
God,  is  not  life— life  wise  and  eternal,  without  temporal  beginning,  without  temporal  end. 
For  both  the  realm  of  bodies,  and  the  whole  sensible  creation,  are,  in  the  Word  of  God,  life 
wise  and  eternal,  so  that,  in  a  way  ineffable  and  incomprehensible  but  yet  credible,  every 
creature  lives  in  the  Word  of  God,  and  in  that  Word  is  life  ;  and  the  divine  Word— since 
outside  of  it  is  nothing— moving  as  it  were  toward  externality,  has  brought  forth  out  of 
itself  all  created  creatures." 

2  III.  23. 

315 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

second  and  third  the  diversity  or  manifold  of  types  and  of  particulars. 
And  all  four  are  alike  God  or  in  God ;  for  "  God  is  the  beginning,  the 
middle,  and  the  end  [i.e.,  source,  process,  and  goal]  of  the  whole 
created  universe ;  not  as  if  it  were  for  Him  three  distinct  things  to  be 
beginning,  middle,  and  goal,  since  these  three  are  in  Him  one;  but 
because  the  movement  of  theological  contemplation  is  threefold."1 
And  what  drives  Erigena  to  adopt  so  vast  and  complex  a  scheme  of 
exposition  is  the  fact  that  he  has  to  work  into  one  system  both  the 
negative  and  the  affirmative  theology. 

As  Erigena  passes  on  to  consider  the  regressus  which  leads  to  the 
fourth  Form  of  Nature,  one  expects  him — in  the  light  of  what  he  had 
said  about  the  first  Form  of  Nature — to  return  finally  and  completely 
to  his  negative  theology,  to  his  Mysticism.  And  that  not  only  as 
moralist  or  preacher,  advising  men  to  lay  aside  all  entanglement  with 
the  particular  and  the  individual,  and  to  find  their  true  being  by 
losing  themselves  in  God;  but  as  a  metaphysician,,  declaring  that,  as 
matter  of  fact,  the  final  outcome  of  the  whole  process  of  the  created 
universe  will  be  its  passage  to  its  rest  in  the  "  still  abysm  "  of  the 
ineffable  God,  in  which  all  things  will  become  God,  and  so  become 
truly  themselves,  by  ceasing  to  be  themselves  as  particular  distinct 
existences.  In  that  way  the  Erigena  of  the  fourth  Form  of  Nature 
would  decisively  complete  what  the  Erigena  of  the  first  Form  of 
Nature  began.  But  as  we  go  on  to  consider  the  details  of  Erigena's 
last  and  highest  view  of  Nature,  his  view  of  the  ultimate  outcome  of 
the  world's  process,  what  we  find  is  that  the  Idealist  has  gained  upon 
the  Mystic.  In  the  ultimate  outcome  of  things,  individuality,  instead 
of  being  negated,  is  made  complete.  Or  rather  individuality  is  in  part 
negated,  in  part  affirmed.  But  the  negation  is  insisted  upon  in  the 
interest  of  the  affirmation ;  it  is  involved,  Erigena  thinks,  in  the  true 
advance  of  human  individuals  to  their  perfection ;  is  involved  in  their 
rise  to  their  Idea,  in  their  return  to  their  true  home  in  the  Word. 

The  regressus  is  described  as  having  two  forms  or  stages.  There 
is,  first,  a  universal  regressus  which  is  the  work  both  of  nature  and  of 
grace,  and,  secondly,  a  special  regressus  which  is  granted  only  to  pure 
hearts  and  is  the  work  of  grace  alone.2  The  former  is  the  return  of 

i  III.  23.  2  V.  23,  36,  38,  39. 

316 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

all  things  to  their  "  beginnings  in  Nature  " ;  i.e.,  it  is  the  exaltation  of 
all  things  to  their  Ideas.,  their  primordial  causes,  and  is  thus  a  general 
return  of  the  third  Form  of  Nature  to  the  second.  This,  as  we  have 
already  seen  in  dealing  with  the  general  principle  which  here  guides 
Erigena's  thinking,  he  regards  as  the  regular  course  of  Nature.  But, 
in  addition  to  that,  there  is  a  special  pressure  upon  him  to  assert  such 
a  universal  return.  The  third  Form  of  Nature  cannot  quite  vindicate 
itself.  It  must  be  condemned  metaphysically,  as  a  realm  of  sense, 
subject  to  dividedness  in  time  and  place ;  and  morally,  because  of  the 
presence  of  evil.  It  is  as  if  Nature  has  in'  the  third  Form  sunk  below 
itself,  so  that  without  possibility  of  exception  the  particular  beings 
into  which  the  inviolable  divine  Nature  has  created  itself,  strive  by 
their  own  natural  motion  back  to  their  Ideas.  There  are  even 
expressions  in  Erigena  which  seem  to  show  him  as  holding  this 
opinion  from  the  point  of  view  of  the,  particular  existences  themselves. 
He  seems  to  feel  that  the  elementary  justice  of  the  universe — that 
"  ultimate  decency  of  things "  in  which  Robert  Louis  Stevenson 
declared  he  would  still  believe  though  he  woke  up  in  hell — requires 
that  the  return  to  the  primordial  causes  should  be  shared  in  by  all 
existences  whatever.  It  rescues,  so  to  speak,  the  individual  existences 
from  the  evils  which  their  particular  and  divided  life  had  forced  upon 
them,  and  restores  them  to  their  own  true  and  normal — in  the 
Platonic  sense,  ideal — being.  They  had  been  something  less  than 
themselves ;  this  return  simply  makes  them  themselves ;  and  therefore 
it  both  is,  and  ought  to  be,  undergone  by  all  existences. 

This  universal  return,  then,  means  that  each  particular  existence 
is  purified  of  the  dividedness  and  imperfection  of  the  third  Form,  and 
returns  to  the  perfection  and  completeness  of  its  eternal  type,  and  thus 
rises  to  the  second  Form  of  Nature,  all  whose  perfect  existences — the 
primordial  causes — are  one  in  the  Word  and  therefore  one  in  God. 
Each  human  being,  for  instance,  will  return  to  the  Idea  of  man;  that 
is,  he  will  rise  above  the  division  of  sex,  and  above  the  limitations  of 
space  and  time,  and  enter  into  the  normal  or  intended  completeness  of 
human  nature.  This,  of  course,  involves  a  great  abstraction;  the 
abstraction  involved  (on  the  common  interpretation  of  Plato)  in 

317 


EBIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

passing  from  an  individual  being  of  this  present  world  to  its  Idea.1 
But  this — even  upon  the  severest  interpretation — is  not  yet  the  com 
plete  abstraction  of  Mysticism.  There  may  be  a  loss  (Erigena  would 
not  call  it  loss)  of  individual  peculiarities  in  rising  to  the  form  of  the 
eternal  type.  But  there  is  no  such  complete  sinking  of  individuality 
as  in  that  mystical  outcome  in  which  all  things  lose  themselves  in  the 
"  still  wilderness  where  never  was  seen  difference.,  neither  Father,  nor 
Son,  nor  Holy  Ghost,"  where  "  there  are  neither  angels  nor  saints 
nor  choirs  nor  heavens,"  where  "  there  is  naught  but  God,"  so  that 
"no  soul  can  come  to  God 'unless  he  becomes  God  as  God  was  before 
the  soul's  creation." 

The  universal  return  involves,  in  Erigena's  view,  two  stages. 
First,  there  is  in  general  the  transformation  of  the  whole  world  of 
sense;  i.e.,  "the  transmutation  of  all  bodies,  whether  those  subject  to 
the  bodily  senses,  or  those  that  by  reason  of  their  exceeding  subtlety 
escape  the  senses ;"  for  "  in  all  that,  which  is  substantially  instituted 
by  the  cause  of  all  things,  nothing  will  be  brought  to  nothingness." 
Secondly,  there  is  the  general  return  of  the  whole  of  human  nature, 
saved  in  Christ,  to  the  pristine  state  of  its  creation,  a  return,  as  it 
were,  to  Paradise,  to  the  dignity  of  the  divine  image,  through  the 
merit  of  Him  whose  blood  was  poured  out  for  the  common  salvation 
of  the  whole  of  humanity.  This  holds  impartially  of  all  men ;  so  that 
no  man  will  be  robbed  of  those  natural  goods,  which  make  up  human 
nature  according  to  its  Idea — which  make  up  what  was  wont  to  be 
called  "  Adamic  perfection."2 

But  in  dealing  with  such  a  universal  return  of  the  world  and  of 
man,  there  at  once  arises  a  great  difficulty.  We  have  already  seen 
how  the  fact  of  evil  drove  Erigena  into  a  sort  of  dualism  in  describing 
the  passage  downward  from  the  second  Form  to  the  Third.  And  now 
that  he  is  tracing  the  reverse  movement,  the  movement  of  all  things 
upward  from  the  third  to  the  second  Form,  a  kindred  difficulty  stands 
in  the  way:  there  is  the  fact  of  evil;  and  there  is  the  church's 
doctrine  of  endless  punishment  in  hell. 

1  There  are,  however,  passages  in  Erigena  which,  if  carried  to  their  logical  conclusion, 
would  make  the  abstraction  greater  even  than  this.    See  the  two  passages  quoted  in  the 
note  to  p.  297  siipra. 

2  See  the  concluding  summary  at  the  end  of  V.  30,  where  the  first  two  forms  belong  to 
the  universal  return  ;  while  the  third  is  that  special  return  which  is  deificatio. 

318 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUKE 

Erigena's  discussion  here  is  really  a  farther  application  of  prin 
ciples  which  we  have  already  had  to  notice.  As  we  have  seen,  he 
regards  Nature  as  one  and  divine  through  all  its  Forms:  the  first 
Form  is  God  as  source;  the  second,  God  creating  Himself  as  the 
eternal  types  or  Ideas;  the  third,  God  creating  Himself  as  particular 
existences.  Hence,  all  that  he  could  say  of  evil  was,  that  it  arises  from 
"perverse  motions  of  the  free  will,"  but  has  no  essential  place  in 
"  Nature."  What  he  now  does  is  to  apply  this  principle  in  a  form 
which  gives  us  the  central  principle  of  the  theologian  whom  he 
admired  so  much;  Origen's  great  principle  of  the  permanence  of  all 
spiritual  substance;  though  Erigena7  s  use  of  it  is  subtle  and  brilliant 
where  Origen's  was  solid  and  profound.  What  God  creates,  urges 
Erigena,  cannot  be  anything  else  than  the  divine  nature  itself.  And 
that  nature  can  neither  perish,  nor  be  subject  to  punishment. 

As  we  go  on  -to  notice  at  slightly  greater  length  the  details  of  the 
discussion,  it  is  due  to  Erigena  to  set  special  emphasis  upon  one  thing : 
this  man  of  the  ninth  century,  writing  in  an  age  when  torture  and 
pain,  when  the  temper  and  the  habit  of  vengeance,  were  familiar 
parts  of  life,  shows  in  his  discussion  a  touch  of  the  charity  of  Christ, 
and  a  vision  of  God  as  exalted  above  mere  vengeance,  which  in  similar 
discussions  in  more  enlightened  ages  have  frequently  been  wanting. 
Erigena  may  have  fallen  into  grave  intellectual  errors;  with  his 
intellectual  inheritance  it  was  inevitable  that  he  should.  But  into  two 
things,  which  may  be  dead  in  the  twentieth  century,  but  were  not  dead 
in  the  nineteenth,  he  did  not  fall :  into  that  darkening  of  the  divine 
righteousness,  which  transforms  it  from  a  righteousness  of  God  into 
a  "  radical  wrong  of  man  " ;  and  into  that  Manichseism  which,  in  its 
very  zeal  to  free  God  from  all  connexion  with  evil,  really  removes  Him 
from  His  place  as  God,  by  viewing  a  power  hostile  to  Him  as  a 
co-eternal  principle  of  the  universe,  and  as  at  last  partly  victorious 
over  Him  and  over  His  purpose. 

Beginning  with  the  prophetic  word,  lest  he  put  forth  his  hand, 
and  take  also  of  the  tree  of  life,  and  eat,  and  live  for  ever, — in  which 
word  "  the  return  of  human  nature  to  the  blessedness  lost  through  sin 
is  most  clearly  promised" — Erigena  goes  on  to  remind  his  disciple 
of  the  conclusion  previously  reached,  "  that  the  Paradise  from  which 

319 


EKIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

man  was  banished  is  nothing  other  than  human  nature  itself  as  created 
in  the  image  of  God;  and  that  it  fell  from  this  its  height  because  it 
disdained  the  command  of  God."  From  this  it  follows  that  "  the 
banishment  of  man  from  Paradise  is  nothing  other  than  the  loss  of 
the  natural  blessedness  for  whose  possession  he  was  created.  For  man 
has  not  lost  his  nature,  which,  being  created  in  the  image  and  likeness 
of  God,  is  necessarily  incorruptible ;  he  lost  only  the  blessedness  which 
he  would  have  attained,  if  he  had  not  scorned  to  be  obedient  to  God."1 
As  the  outward  form  of  man  may  be  disfigured  by  leprosy  and  yet 
remain  the  form  of  man,  so  human  nature  by  its  high-minded 
disobedience  is  hatefully  disfigured,  but  does  not  cease  to  be  human 
nature.  And  "  when  it  is  freed  from  this  leprosy  through  the  healing 
grace  of  God,  it  will  be  called  again  to  its  pristine  beauty.  Nay,  one 
may  even  say,  that  the  nature  created  in  the  image  of  God  never  has 
lost,  never  can  lose,  the  living  strength  (vigor em)  of  its  beauty,  and 
the  integrity  of  its  essence.  For  the  divine  form  remains  unalterable 
for  ever;  and  yet,  as  a  punishment  for  sin,  it  has  become  capable  of 
things  corruptible  " — capable  of  the  change  and  particularity  of  the 
present  world.2  Hence,  as  was  indicated  in  a  passage  alread}r  quoted,3 
we  must  believe  that  in  the  banishment  of  man  from  Eden,  it  was 
God's  mercy,  rather  than  His  punitive  righteousness,  that  was  active. 
For  it  was  God's  purpose  to  regenerate  and  illumine  man,  and  make 
him  worthy  to  come  to  the  tree  of  life,  from  which  he  had  been  driven, 
and  to  eat  of  it  so  that  he  might  not  perish,"  but  might  live  eternally. 
Therefore  it  was  that  the  cherubim  were  set  in  their  station  at  the 
east  of  Eden;  for  the  cherubim  signify  the  Word  of  God,  in  which 
the  treasures  of  knowledge  and  of  wisdom  are  hidden,  and  which 
without  interruption  stands  ready  for  man's  gaze,  so  that  human 
nature  may  be  warned  and  illuminated  and  purified  and  led  back  at 
last  to  unflawed  completeness.  And  likewise  the  flaming  sword 
signifies  the  Word  of  God,  which  consumes  our  sins,  and  purifies  our 
natures,  and  at  the  same  time  distinguishes  between  our  nature  and 
that  which  cleaves  to  it  through  the  guilt  of  sin,  and  hatefully 
disfigures  it,  and  makes  it  unlike  the  Creator.  So  that  the  flaming 
sword  applies  itself  ineffcibili  sua  dementia  et  misericordia  to  the 

1  V.  1,  2.  2  V.  6.  3  Supra,  pp.  309,  310. 

320 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

healing  of  human  nature.  Always  before  the  eyes  of  our  soul  stand 
the  cherubim  with  the  naming  sword  to  keep  the  way  of  the  tree  of 
life — to  keep  the  way  of  the  tree  of  life,  not  in  the  sense  of  forbidding 
our  access,  but  in  the  sense  of  preventing  us  from  ever  forgetting  that 
tree,  so  that  continually  we  may  have  before  the  eyes  of  our  spirit 
both  the  tree  itself  and  the  way  of  approach  to  it.1 

So  Erigena  agrees  with  the  opinion  of  "  the  great  theologian 
Gregory,"  that  "  evil  is  not  so  strong  that  it  can  overcome  the  power 
of  good."  It  cannot,  like  good,  proceed  to  infinity;  it  is  sternly 
restricted  within  necessary  limits.  It  "  cannot  be  perpetual,  but  by 
the  necessity  of  things  is  to  reach  an  appointed  bound,  and  is  some 
time  to  cease."  Just  because  the  divine  goodness  is  eternal  and 
infinite,  its  opposite  cannot  be  eternal  or  infinite.2 

But  does  not  this  bring  us,  asks  the  Scholar,  into  contradiction  with 
the  accepted  teaching  that  human  nature  is  partly  (in  the  elect)  to 
be  redeemed,  partly  (in  the  godless)  to  be  damned  to  eternal  fire?3 
Erigena  replies  by  asserting  in  accordance  with  the  principle  already 
noted,  that  God  punishes  no  nature  which  He  has  created,  whether  in 
human  or  devilish  substance ;  in  all  creatures,  God  punishes  only  that 
which  He  has  not  made,  namely,  the  irrational  motions  of  the  perverse 
will.  Of  the  evil  spirits,  that  alone  which  was  created  in  them  by  God 
Most  High  can  remain,  and  is  in  no  wise  subject  to  punishment ;  but 
that  which  is  not  from  God,  namely,  their  evil,  will  perish,  in  order 
that  an  evil  permanent  and  co-eternal  with  the  good,  may  not  have 
place  in  any  creature  whether  human  or  angelic.  The  same  is  true  of 
death  and  misery,  lest  something  hostile  to  life  and  blessedness,  and 
co-eternal  with  these,  should  arise.4  And  when  it  is  said  that  the  last 
enemy  will  be  destroyed — the  last  enemy  with  whose  destruction  all 
sorrow  and  death,  all  enmities  and  separations,  will  cease — this  does 
not  mean  that  his  substance,  created  of  God,  is  to  perish,  but  that  his 
hostile  purpose  and  will,  which  proceed  not  from  God,  but  from 
himself,  are  to  perish.  He  is  to  be  destroyed,  not  in  the  sense  that  he 
will  no  longer  exist,  but,  as  "the  great  Origen"  perceived,  in  the 
sense  that  he  will  no  longer  be  the  Enemy  and  Death.5 

It  is  putting  the  same  general  position  into  another,  and  a  very 

i  V.  2.  2  V.  26.  3  V.  27.  *  V.  28.  5  V.  27. 

22  321 


EEIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

telling,  form,  when  Erigena  urges  that  God  is  the  only  principle  of 
eternal  existence,  so  that  anything  which  is  eternal  can  have  its  being 
only  in  God  and  through  God ;  and,  therefore,  evil  cannot  be  eternal 
— cannot  be  an  absolute  and  final  principle  of  the  universe.1 

His  discussion  of  "that  eternal  fire,  the  torture,  the  burning 
sulphurous  pool/'  is  what  might  be  expected  from  the  principles  just 
noted.  In  gentleness  and  spirituality,  in  freedom  from  heathen 
imaginations  and  from  the  spirit  of  savagery,  this  theologian  of  the 
ninth  century  stands  far  above  many  teachers  of  a  later  day.  The 
fire  is  that  of  undying  memory,  of  late  repentance,  of  earthly 
imaginations  and  a  love  for  earthly  things  which  can  no  longer  find 
any  corresponding  object.2  But  if  it  be  asked  how  such  memories  and 
imaginations  can  retain  a  place  in  "  Nature  " — so  that  that  which  lies 
outside  of  Nature  and  is  contrary  to  it,  is  endured  by  the  power  of 
Nature,  and  within  Nature  is  punished,  Nature  itself  remaining 
always  and  altogether  inviolate  in  itself — Erigena  can  only  answer 
by  the  theologian's  recourse  to  mystery;  we  must  give  place  to  the 
incomprehensible  power  of  God,  and  honour  it  with  silence,  for  at  its 
entrance  reason  and  insight  are  rebuked.3 

When  this  sad  problem  has  been  discussed,  Erigena  is  able  to 
return  to  the  real  object  and  delight  of  his  thought — to  tracing  the 
course  of  "  Nature,"  the  course  of  the  normal  and  inviolate  order  of 
the  world.  The  way  in  which  he  works  out  the  universal  regressus 
with  which  we  are  now  concerned,  may  be  briefly  indicated  as  follows : 

The  process  itself  is  one  of  synthesis  or  unifying.  The  nature 
of  this  unifying  Erigena  indicates  thus:  "...  with  regard  to 
the  unifying,  this  must  of  necessity  always  be  heeded,  that  what  is 
seen  to  be  lower  is  taken  up  (moveatur)  into  that  which  is  higher, 
that  is  to  say,  better;  but  a  better  never  passes  over  into  a  meaner, 

1  v.  so. 

2  Of  the  Last  Judgment,  too,    Erigena   forbids   sensuous   images.      The    book,  for 
instance,  is  that  power  of  memory  of  which  Augustine  speaks  in  the  words :  "  There  is  a 
divine  power  of  the  understanding,  through  which  it  comes  to  pass  that  for  every  man 
his  works,  whether  they  are  good  or  evil,  are  in  their  totality  called  back  into  his  memory, 
and  with  marvellous  quickness  are  looked  upon  by  the  eyes  of  his  soul,  so  that  the  knowl 
edge  accuses  or  excuses  the  conscience,  and  thus  each  soul  of  man  is  judged."     (Quoted 
inDeDiv.Nat.  V.  38.) 

3  V.  32,  33. 

322 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATUEE 

i.e.,  turns  back  in  the  renewal  of  the  natures ;  else  what  would  come 
to  pass  would  be  not  unification,  but  division."1  In  the  universal 
regressus  this  unification  takes  place  in  the  two  stages  already  referred 
to :  the  unification  of  all  natures  in  man ;  and  the  return  of 
man  to  his  natural  place  in  the  divine  Word. 

First,  all  the  things  of  this  world  are  created  in  man;  so  that  in 
man's  return  to  the  second  Form  of  Nature,  they  return  also;  or,  as 
Erigena  sometimes  puts  it,  the  sensible  things  of  the  present  world, 
being  included  in  human  nature,  participate  in  the  resurrection.2  This 
view  of  man's  position  in  the  universe  is  found  in  many  forms  in 
Erigena.  At  times,  following  Maximus  the  Confessor,  he  regards  man 
as  a  harmony  of  opposites,  as  the  mediation  and  synthesis  of  all 
creatures,  in  whom  the  extremest  antitheses  of  Nature  are  brought  to 
unity,  and  through  whom  therefore  they  can  advance  to  their  final 
unity  in  God.3  Again,  man  is  to  Erigena  the  microcosm  that  corre 
sponds  to  the  macrocosm.  This  insight  which  is  essential  to  any 
adequate  theory  of  knowledge  and  usually  enters  philosophy  in  that 
connexion,  is  to  Erigena  the  basis  of  man's  return  to  God,  and  of 
the  return  of  the  world  to  God  in  and  through  man.  He  in  one  place 
makes  a  fourfold  division  of  all  created  life — angelic  intellect,  reason 
as  in  man,  sensible  life  as  in  animals,  vitality  without  thought  or  sense 
as  in  plants — and  shows  how  all  these,  not  in  mere  external  combina 
tion,  but  in  true  synthesis,  are  in  man;  so  that,  in  the  homely 
expression  which  Erigena  loves  to  use,  man  is  creaturarum  omnium 
officina — the  workshop  of  all  the  creatures — and  in  him  the  whole  of 
Nature  is  contained.4  And,  Erigena  thinks,  this  must  be  so;  unless 
it  were,  unless  God  "  created  every  creature  in  man,"  man  would  not 
be  truly  "  created  in  the  image  and  likeness  of  God."5 

Then,  secondly,  human  nature,  which  thus  gathers  up  into  itself  all 
the  world,  is  itself  taken  up  into  the  Word.  "  He  came  forth  from  the 
Father,  and  came  into  the  world,  taking  upon  Himself  the  nature  of 
man  in  which  the  whole  world  consists  (in  qua  totus  mundus  sub- 
sistit)  ;  for  there  is  nothing  in  the  world  which  is  not  included  in 

ill.  8.  2V.  23.  3  II.  3-9.  *  III.  37  ;  IV.  5. 

5  IV.  7.— Erigena  goes  on  to  say,  with  a  naivete  very  unusual  to  him,  that  he  absolutely 
does  not  know  why,  in  preference  to  all  the  other  visible  and  invisible  creatures,  God 
should  choose  precisely  man,  as  the  creature  to  be  made  in  His  own  image. 

323 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

human  nature.  And  again  He  left  the  world  and  went  to  the  Father ; 
that  is,  by  union  with  His  Deity,  which  is  equal  to  the  Father,  He 
exalted  the  human  nature,  which  He  had  received,  high  above  all 
things  visible  and  invisible,  above  all  heavenly  powers,  above  every 
thing  that  can  be  said  and  comprehended.  For,  while  He  saved,  wholly 
in  Himself  and  wholly  in  the  whole  race  of  men,  the  whole  human 
nature  which  wholly  he  had  taken  upon  Himself,  establishing  some 
again  in  the  previous  condition  of  Nature  [the  universal  regressus], 
but  exalting  others  by  pre-eminence  above  Nature  and  deifying  them 
[the  special  return  of  pure  hearts]  ;  yet  in  no  other  but  Himself  is 
humanity  made  one  with  Deity  in  unity  of  substance,  so  as,  trans 
formed  into  Deity  itself,  to  transcend  all  things."1  In  another  place, 
after  dealing  with  an  apparent  deviation  in  Augustine,  both  from  his 
own  opinion  as  expressed  in  other  writings,  and  from  the  teachings 
of  his  predecessors  among  the  Fathers,  "  Ambrosius  and  the  theologian 
Gregory/'  he  goes  on :  "  I,  however,  who  detract  from  no  one  and 
strive  with  no  one,  unhesitatingly  understand  our  Lord's  own  words : 
I  and  the  Father  are  one,  as  spoken  not  of  His  divinity  alone,  but  of 
His  whole  substance,  of  God  and  man  together."2 

Through  Christ,  furthermore,  it  is  that  man  is  still  able  to  perform 
this  great  function,  even  though  he  is  fallen.  For  when  fallen  human 
nature,  in  the  darkness  of  its  perverted  will,  forgot  both  its  Creator 
and  its  own  original  being;  when  it  lay  in  wretched  death,  in  the 
abysmal  dark  of  ignorance,  in  farthest  alienation  from  its  own  true 
nature  and  from  its  Creator,  in  shameful  likeness  to  irrational  and 
mortal  creatures;  then  "no  one  was  able  to  redeem  human  nature 
from  this  condition,  to  call  it  back,  to  renew  it,  and  to  establish  it 
again  in  that  earlier  state  from  which  it  had  fallen;  but  the  divine 
Wisdom,  which  created  it,  and  received  it  into  unity  with  its  own 
substance  in  order  to  maintain  it  in  that  state,  has  freed  it  from  all 
misery.  Let  it  not  disturb  thee,  therefore,  when  it  is  said  that  human 
nature  is  everywhere  whole  in  itself,  both  the  [divine]  image  whole  in 
the  animal,  and  the  animal  whole  in  the  [divine]  image.  Everything 
which  its  Creator  created  primordially  in  it  remains  whole  and 
inviolate,  but  lies  as  yet  concealed,  awaiting  the  manifestation  of  the 

1  V.  25.  V.  37. 

324 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

sons  of  God."1  The  same  view  of  Christ's  general  redemptive  work  as 
the  restoration  of  universal  human  nature  to  its  beginning — i.e.,  to  its 
Idea,  its  primordial  form  as  manifest  in  Eden — is  seen  when  Erigena 
points  out  that  the  Redeemer  of  the  world  was  free  from  that 
ignorance  in  which  we  are  sunken  at  our  birth,  "  not  only  because  he 
was  the  Wisdom  of  the  Father,  for  which  there  is  no  hidden  thing, 
but  because  He  took  upon  Him  unstained  humanity,  in  order  to  purify 
the  stained;  not  as  if  He  took  upon  Himself  some  other  humanity 
than  that  which  He  restored,  but  because  he  alone  remained  without 
stain  in  it,  and  was  preserved  for  the  healing  of  the  wound  of 
corrupted  nature  in  its  most  secret  grounds.  For  the  whole  [of 
Nature]  came  to  ruin  in  all, — save  in  the  case  of  Him  in  whom  alone 
it  remained  incorruptible.  Therefore,  He  Himself  is  become  the 
greatest  example  of  grace,  not  because  some  indulgence  was  made  to 
human  nature  on  His  account,  but  because  He  alone  among  all, 
without  previous  merit,  was  bound  in  unity  of  substance  with  the 
Word  of  God,  so  that  in  Him  all  the  elect,  drawing  from  the  fulness 
of  His  grace,  become  Sons  of  God  and  partakers  of  the  divine 
substance."2 

Such,  then,  is  the  universal  regressus,  in  which  all  existences  are 
taken  up  into  man  and  man  into  the  Word.  The  following  passage- 
one  from  among  many — indicates  the  transition  from  the  general  to 
the  special  return.  "  ...  By  the  ten  virgins  who  went  to  meet  the 
bridegroom,  is  represented  the  universal  return  of  the  whole  human 
rnce  (totius  humanae  numerositatis  generalis  .  .  .  reversio) 
to  the  pristine  condition  of  Nature;  but  by  the  five  wise  ones,  the 
special  return  of  all  the  saints.  For  the  number  of  the  elect  is  a 
species  of  the  human  race.  So  that  what  is  indicated  is  not  merely 
the  return  to  the  ancient  beginning  of  Nature  in  generalitatem 
humanitatis,  but  also  the  ineffable  ascent  beyond  Nature  into  God 
Himself  in  specialitate  deificationis.  All,  as  was  said,  are  to  return 
to  Paradise,  but  not  all  are  to  eat  of  the  tree  .of  life  [i.e.,  the  Word]  ; 
or  at  least,  all  are  to  receive  of  the  tree  of  life,  but  not  equally.  For 
only  a  fool  is  ignorant  of  the  fact,  that  natural  goods,  of  which  all 
will  be  equally  partakers  [in  the  universal  return],  are  the  fruit  of 

i  IV.  5,  6.  2  IV.  9. 

325 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

the  tree  of  life.  For  Christ,,  as  was  discussed  earlier,  is  called 
ttav  Zvhov,  id  est  omne  lignum,  because  He  omnium  bonorum 
lignum  est  fructiferum,  being  Himself  every  good  thing  and  the 
bestower  of  all  good.  All  men  will  enjoy  his  fruit  through  the 
universal  participation  in  the  goods  of  Nature;  but  his  elect,  lifted 
high  above  all  Nature,  will  enjoy  the  special  height  of  deification."1 

The  special  return,  then,  takes  place  only  for  purified  souls  and 
only  through  the  operation  of  divine  grace  as  distinct  from  Nature. 
It  consists  in  the  return  of  the  soul  not  only  to  its  Idea — its  "  begin 
ning  in  Nature " — but  also  its  elevation,  far  above  every  natural 
dignity,  to  its  goal  with  God,  as  the  cause  of  all  things.2  This  is 
realised  only  in  the  men  who  "  not  merely  are  to  ascend  to  the  height 
of  the  Nature  present  in  them,  but  also,  through  the  riches  of  the 
divine  grace  which  through  Christ  and  in  Christ  is  given  to  His 
chosen,  are  to  pass  beyond  all  laws  and  limits  of  Nature  superessen- 
tially  into  God  Himself,  and  become  one  in  Him  and  with  Him.7'3 
The  universal  return  brings  all  men  to  those  natural  goods  of  human 
nature  which,  like  all  the  Ideas,  have  their  being  in  Christ;  but  this 
special  return  brings  those  who  participate  in  it  to  "  the  supernatural 
grace  and  joy  of  deificatio  "  wherein  the  souls  that  are  made  perfect 
are  glorified  by  the  supernatural  grace  of  the  contemplation  of  God." 
One  part  of  men — represented  by  the  five  foolish  virgins  in  the 
parable — will  return  only  to  Adamic  perfection;  to  the  condition  of 
man  before  he  sinned,  when  the  goods  which  he  possessed  were  purely 
natural  and  could  not  yet  be  called  virtues.  But  the  other  part  of 
mankind  will  rise  to  that  height  to  which  man,  if  he  had  continued 
free  from  sin,  would  have  been  lifted  by  grace.  To  this  height,  which 
is  the  "  spiritual  marriage  of  the  bridegroom,"  no  one  is  admitted 
save  those  whose  souls  are  "bright  with  the  light  of  wisdom  and 
glowing  with  the  flames  of  divine  love."  It  is  above  Nature,  and 
therefore  unattainable  to  merely  natural  beauty  or  good.  To  it  the 
human  spirit  is  uplifted  only  by  "grace,  and  the  merit  of  obedience 
toward  the  divine  commands,  and  the  merit  of  the  purest  knowledge 
of  God  which  in  this  life  it  is  possible  to  gain  from  Scripture  and  the 
created  world."4 

1  V.  3?.  2  V.  38.  3  V.  39.  4  V.  38. 

326 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

The  special  regressus,  which  thus  takes  up  into  itself  the  whole 
returning  movement  of  Nature  and  at  the  same  time  goes  beyond 
Nature,  Erigena  is  careful  to  trace  through  its  stages.  First,  within 
the  limits  of  Nature,  earthly  body  is  transformed  into  vital  move 
ment,  vital  movement  into  sense,  sense  into  reason,  reason  into  spirit 
"  in  which  consists  the  end  of  the  whole  rational  creature  " ;  so  that 
the  five  natural  constituents  of  man's  being,  by  the  taking  up  of  the 
lower  into  the  higher,  become  one — inferioribus  semper  a  superioribus 
consummates,  non  ut  non  sint,  sed  ut  unum  sint.  Then  three  "  super 
natural  and  superessential "  stages  of  ascent,  which  are  in  God,  com 
plete  this  return  of  the  soul.  Of  these  "  the  first  is  the  passing  of 
spirit  into  the  knowledge  of  all  the  things  that  are  next  below  God; 
the  second  is  the  transition  from  this  science  into  wisdom,  that  is, 
into  the  innermost  vision  of  truth  so  far  as  it  is  granted  to  the 
creature;  the  third  and  highest  is  the  supernatural  sinking  (occasus — 
the  going  down,  as  of  the  sun)  of  the  completely  purified  souls  into 
God  Himself,  and,  .as  it  were,  the  darkness  of  the  incomprehensible 
and  unapproachable  light,  wherein  are  hidden  the  causes  of  all 
things.  And  then  will  the  night  be  bright  like  the  day;  that  is,  the 
most  hidden  divine  mysteries  will  in  ineffable  wise  be  made  open  to 
the  blessed  and  illuminated  intelligences."1 

We  have  already  seen  that  the  first  or  universal  stage  of  the 
regressus  cannot  be  called  mystical.  And  upon  the  whole  the  same 
must  be  said  of  this.  True,  the  purified  soul  is  described  as  "  sinking 
into  God."  But  the  statement  which  immediately  follows,  that  to 
these  blessed  souls  the  most  hidden  mysteries  will  be  made  open,  seems 
to  imply  the  retention  of  individual  selfhood.  And  this  reading  of 
the  passage  is  distinctly  confirmed  by  other  passages.  Early  in  the 
fifth  Book,  Erigena,  in  dealing  with  the  return  of  human  nature, 
distinguishes  five  stages  (the  number  differs  at  different  places). 
The  fourth  is  when  the  spirit,  and  the  whole  human  nature,  return  to 
the  primordial  causes ;  this  is,  of  course,  the  sharing  of  human  nature 
in  the  universal  regressus,  which  has  already  been  dealt  with.  The 
fifth  is  when  Nature  itself  with  its  causes  moves  itself  to  God,  "  as  air 
to  light."  Then  Erigena  goes  on :  "  God  will  be  all  in  all,  when 

1  V.  39. 

327 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

nothing  will  be  except  God  alone.  By  this  I  do  not  attempt  to  assert 
that  the  substance  of  things  is  to  perish,  but  that  rather  it  is  to  return 
by  the  steps  which  have  been  mentioned  to  a  better  condition.  For 
how  can  that  perish  which  is  destined  to  return  to  a  better  state? 
The  transformation  of  human  nature  into  God  is,  then,  not  to  be 
regarded  as  a  perishing  of  its  substance,  but  as  a  wonderful  and 
ineffable  return  into  that  pristine  condition,  which  it  had  lost  through 
transgression."1  A  little  later  in  the  same  chapter  he  points  out  that 
the  bodily  substance  will  pass  over  into  soul,  "  not  in  order  that  what 
is  may  be  lost,  but  that  it  may  be  saved  in  a  better  essence.  The  same 
is  true  of  the  soul  itself,  that  it  so  raises  itself  to  intelligence  as  in  it 
to  be  preserved  fairer  and  more  like  God.  Not  otherwise  is  it  with 
the  transition,  I  will  not  say  of  all,  but  only  of  rational  essences,  into 
God,  in  whom  all  things  will  find  their  goal  and  be  one.  But  what 
has  been  said  about  the  unifying  of  human  nature  without  the 
destruction  of  the  proper  nature  (proprietatis)  of  the  individual 
substances,  we  may  confirm  by  the  view  of  the  sainted  Maximus." 
Then  he  quotes  from  Maximus  a  passage,  in  which  it  is  pointed  out 
that  when  men  are  "  deified  "  through  the  grace  of  the  incarnate  God, 
"  the  whole  man  remains  in  soul  and  body  through  Nature,  while 
through  grace  he  has  become  in  soul  and  body  altogether  God." 
"  Thus,"  Erigena  urges,  "the  peculiarity  (proprietor)  of  the  natures 
will  remain  intact  without  prejudice  to  their  unity,  and  neither  will 
the  unity  of  the  natures  be  removed  by  the  peculiarity,  nor  the 
peculiarity  by  the  unity."  Still  later  he  argues  that  "  a  unifying  of 
human  nature,  with  the  preservation  of  the  proprietates  of  the  indi 
vidual  substances,  is  possible."2 

IV.  8. 

2  V.  13.— Such  passages  show  Erigena  reaching  out  after  the  organic  categories  which 
neither  he  nor  his  age  could  possess,  and  for  want  of  which  his  thinking  was  compelled  to 
fall  apart,  on  the  one  side  toward  the  negative  theology,  on  the  other  toward  the  affirma 
tive.  And  neither  side  could  decisively  prevail.  For  on  the  one  hand,  without  the  organic 
and  evolutionary  categories  the  true  scientific  feeling  for  the  unity  of  existence  must  lead 
toward  Mysticism.  And  on  the  other  hand,  the  manifold  world,  with  its  divine  presences, 
absolutely  refuses  to  be  dismissed.  So  that  Erigena  is  really  in  the  grasp  of  logical  neces 
sity.  He  must  deal  with  the  problem  of  the  Many  and  the  One  ;  and  the  only  possible 
course  was,  with  regard  to  the  Many  to  be  either  a  Pantheist  like  the  Spinoza  of  the 
"  second  metaphysic,"  or  an  Idealist  (Erigena  was  both);  and  with  regard  to  the  One,  to 
be  a  Mystic,  so  far  as  a  Christian  i  heologian  of  the  ninth  century,  unable  to  call  for  the 
ultimate  extinction  of  individuality,  could  be. 

328 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

In  another  way,  also — a  very  different  way — Erigena's  conclusion 
varies  from  that  which  the  beginning  would  have  led  one  to  expect. 
He  began  with,  and  throughout  the  whole  discussion  he  continually 
insists  upon,  the  great  and  necessary  thought  of  Nature  as  one ;  which 
implies  that  Nature  and  Grace  are  one,  the  ways  of  Nature  being 
manifestations  of  Grace,  and  Grace  achieving  its  purposes  through 
the  eternal  orderliness  of  Nature.  But,  as  we  so  often  have  had  to 
notice,  he  had  not  made  his  way,  except  in  flashes  of  sudden  and 
brilliant  insight,  to  the  organic  point  of  view.  Hence  in  passing 
down  from  the  second  Form  to  the  third,  he  was  obliged  to  admit  a 
rift  in  the  unity  of  Nature — the  coming  into  the  world  of  something 
which  is  absolutely  unnatural,  namely,  evil.  Then,  in  tracing  the 
reverse  movement  this  separation  necessarily  reappears,  and,  in  the 
way  which  we  have  just  seen,  Grace  is  set  apart  from  Nature  as 
superior  to  it.  Erigena's  thinking,  in  short,  when  its  last  word  is 
compared  with  its  first,  is  at  once  a  call  for,  and  a  prophecy  of,  the 
day  when  the  human  mind,  having  entered  into  possession  of  more 
adequate  categories,  should  be  able  to  repeat  the  assertion  which  he 
made,  but  could  not  maintain:  the  assertion  of  the  unity  of  Nature 
and  Grace,  Law  being  a  work  of  Grace,  Grace  being  the  principle  of 
Nature. 

In  the  fourth  Form  of  Nature,  then,  which  is  the  outcome  of  the 
process  of  the  world,  there  is  a  universal  return  of  the  human  race, 
and  of  that  whole  creation  which  was  made  in  it  and  for  it,  to  the 
primordial  causes,  and  then,  beyond  this,  there  is  the  special  return 
to  God  Himself  of  those  who  are  worthy  to  enjoy  that  pure  partici 
pation.  In  this  double  Sabbath — the  universal  Sabbath  in  all  the 
works  of  God,  the  special  Sabbath  of  Sabbaths  in  holy  angels  and  holy 
men — the  house  of  God  will  be  filled,  and  in  it  each  will  find  his  own 
place,  "  some  below,  some  above,  some  in  the  heights  of  Nature,  others 
exalted  above  all  power  of 'Nature  with  God  Himself.  And  thus  that 
great  feast  will  be  set  in  order  and  celebrated,  from  which  the 
substance  of  nothing  that  is  (for  substances  draw  their  being  from 
God)  will  be  shut  out,  and  to  which  the  defect  (vitium)  of  nothing 
that  is  (because  defects  have  not  their  origin  from  God)  will  be 

329 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

introduced.  For  Nature  will  be  purified,  defect  winnowed  away,  the 
substantial  germs  of  being  preserved;  by  the  flame  of  the  divine 
judgment  the  chaff  of  transgressions  will  be  burnt  away,  the  concealed 
things  of  darkness  illumined,  and  God  will  be  seen  as  all  in  all."1 

Such  was  the  view  of  the  world  and  of  our  life  taken  by  John 
Scotus  Erigena,  a  man  of  the  ninth  century.    His  intellect,  as  revealed 
in  the  De  Divisions  Naturae,  is  an  intellect  subtle  and  powerful  and 
daring;  one  that  can  hold  its  steady  way  through  a  great  argument 
and  yet  flash  into  keen  and  original  suggestions  at  every  step.    And 
with  all  that  originality  went  the  greater  qualities  without  which 
originality  is  the  passing    novelty  of  a  day.     Habitually,  Erigena's 
mind  sought    the  eternal;    so  much  so,    that    one  of  the    deepest 
impressions  left  upon  the  reader's  mind  by  the  De  Divisione  Naturae, 
in  spite  of  all  its  delight  in  argument,  is  that  of  a  strange  peace  which 
knows  nothing  of    contention,  nothing  of    reviling,  nothing  of    the 
furious  spirit  of  the  theologians,  nothing  even  of  the  contemporary 
world — as  if  the  book  had  been  written  in  a  solitude  which  left  no 
object  for  a  man's  thoughts  but  God  and  the  eternal  things  of  God. 
And  then,  too,   (probably  by  reason  as  much  of  instinct  and   native 
sympathy  as  of  knowledge),  Erigena's  was  a  comprehensive  mind,  in 
the  sense  tha.t  the  three  great  theologies  which  have  swayed  human 
life,  but  for  which  in  his  day  no  clear  distinction  and  reconciliation 
had  been  worked  out,  lived  in  it  side  by  side.    With  full  earnestness, 
Erigena  gave   himself  to   the    mystical    theology,   which  puts   God 
altogether  beyond  the  apprehension  of  reason,  and  union  with  God 
altogether  beyond  the  normal  forms  and  energies  of  our  experience. 
But  with  equal  earnestness  he  gave  himself  to  the  affirmative  theology, 
upon  whose  positive  view  of  the  relation  of  the  world  to  God  the 
ordered  universe  appears  as  a  self -unfolding  or  self-communication  of 
God.    And  this  latter  theology  was  present  in  him  in  both  the  forms 
which  historically  it  has  assumed,  the  Pantheistic  and  the  Idealistic; 
forms  represented  in  modern  philosophy,  the  one  by  the  Spinoza  of 
the  "  second  metaphysic,"  the  other  by  Hegel.     For  want  of  a  clear 
possession  of  the  higher  categories  he  is  often  driven,  not,  indeed,  to 

1  V.  38. 
330 


ERIGENA:    THE    DIVISION    OF    NATURE 

Spinoza's  formula  of  substance,  attribute,  and  mode,  but  yet,  none  the 
less  really,  toward  the  essential  movement  of  thought  of  Pantheism; 
is  often  driven  to  view  the  process  of  the  universe  as  an  unfolding 
from  above,  of  such  a  kind  that  the  presence  in  it  of  anything  not 
directly  and  plainly  of  divine  nature  constitutes  a  problem  of  hopeless 
difficulty.  But  he  continually  has  glimpses  of  Hegel's  greater  way; 
continually  rises  to  the  view  of  the  history  of  the  universe  as  a  process 
in  which  Absolute  Eeason  realises  its  purpose  of  righteousness  and  of 
good,  by  "  externalising  and  diversifying  itself  " ;  by  giving  rise,  that 
is  to  say,  to  individual  existences,  to  whom  life  and  the  struggle  of 
life  are  real,  and  through  whose  labours  and  struggles  there  is  slowly 
built  up  that  City  of  God  in  which,  just  because  men  have  come  to  the 
fulness  of  their  individuality,  God  is  truly  all  in  all. 

Far  apart  as  these  three  theologies  lie  from  one  another,  Erigena 
found  in  himself  a  kinship  of  soul  for  each  of  them ;  to  each  of  them 
he  gave  himself ;  and  so  became  one  of  those  men  whose  vocation  it  is 
to  attempt  the  impossible,  and  by  that  attempt  to  serve  the  world  and 
carry  forward  its  history  to  new  stages.  But  as  one  takes  leave  of 
him,  it  is  not  of  the  subtlety  and  brilliance  of  his  mind,  nor  even  of 
his  remarkable  historical  position,  that  one  cares  last  to  speak.  The 
best  final  word  to  say  of  him  is,  that  he  had  high  thoughts  concerning 
God;  and  therefore  he  had  high  thoughts  concerning  man  and  the 
destiny  of  man ;  concerning  the  destiny  even  of  the  men  whose  souls 
are  most  shrouded  in  darkness. 


331 


THE  THEISM  OF   ST.  THOMAS 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS. 

THE  "  Theism  "  of  a  great  master  of  systematic  theology  ought  in 
propriety  to  mean  the  whole  body  of  his  thought.  It  ought  to  signify 
his-  whole  view  of  the  world  and  of  man.  For  the  world,  and  its  citizen 
man,,  have  their  being  from  God  and  in  God;  the  very  individuality 
and  freedom  of  man  are  themselves  a  communication  of  His  nature 
on  the  part  of  God.  And  from  this  it  follows  that  the  view  of  God, 
the  view  of  the  nature  of  the  world,  the  view  of  the  meaning  of  man's 
life,  are  correlative  views.  The  form  which  any  one  of  them  has  come 
to  assume  in  one's  mind  determines,  if  one's  thinking  really  is 
systematic,  the  form  which  the  others  must  assume.  Furthermore, 
that  which  in  the  order  of  reality  is  primary  and  determinative,  is 
God;  and  that  order  of  reality  the  order  of  our  conception  ought  so 
far  as  possible  to  reproduce.  It  is  true  that  in  the  way  of  natural 
reason  we  rise  to  the  apprehension  of  God  through  the  world  and 
through  our  own  souls.  But  once  a  conception  of  God  is  reached  by 
us,  either  it  becomes  the  organising  and  determinative  principle  of 
all  our  thinking  about  the  world  and  man,  or  else  our  thought  (for 
honourable  reasons,  it  may  indeed  be — when  the  terrible  mysteries  of 
life  have  put  us  to  silence,  and  we  have  but  faith  where  we  "  cannot 
know")  is  fragmentary  and  not  systematic. 

So  that  a  study  of  the  Theism  of  St.  Thomas  ought  to  be  a  study 
of  the  whole  body  of  his  theology,  down  to  its  last  discussion  of  nature 
or  the  state.  But  that  is  not  possible  here ;  it  is  necessary  in  the  few 
pages  that  remain  to  fall  below  that  justice,  and  to  confine  the 
discussion  to  St.  Thomas'  "  conception  of  God  "  in  the  usual  limited 
meaning  of  that  expression.  In  dealing  with  it  what  we  shall  find  is, 
first  a  doctrine  concerning  God  which  logically  implies,  though  it 
does  not  expressly  formulate,  a  view  akin  to  Concrete  or  Objective 
Idealism;  but  secondly,  this  view  crossed  by  a  dualism  similar  in 
motive  to  that  which  already  we  have  seen  in  Plato  and  Aristotle — 

335 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

the  dualism  between  the  perfect  and  eternal  God,  and  this  imperfect 
and  temporal  world. 

The  references  are  to  the  smaller,  or  philosophical,  Summa  which 
St.  Thomas  wrote  "  contra  gentiles."  Any  references  to  the  larger — 
the  theological — Summa  are  indicated  by  the  necessary  abbreviation. 

In  the  book  Contra  Gentiles  we  find,  at  the  point  to  which  our 
task  specially  leads  us,  the  following  reasoning  developed.  St. 
Thomas  has  by  the  preceding  argument  been  led  to  declare  that  all 
things  movable,  all  things  subject  to  KLV^GI?,  i.e.,  the  whole  process 
of  the  phenomenal  world,  must  be  referred  back  tp  unum  primum 
movens  seipsum.  But  can  we  form  any  conception  of  a  self -mover? 
Yes,  we  can;  and  in  the  forty-fourth  chapter  of  the  first  Book  St. 
Thomas  proceeds  to  do  so.  That  which  moves  itself,  that  in  which 
est  movere  et  non  moveri,  does  so  per  appetitum  et  appreliensionem. 
But  with  regard  to  the  omnium  primum  movens  (quod  Deum 
dicimus),  the  desire  cannot  be  for  any  particular  or  sensuous  good, 
for  anything  bonum  et  appetibile  ut  hie  et  mine.  On  the  contrary, 
the  desire  must  be  that  of  the  First  Mover  for  Himself.  In  all  His 
activities,  He  is  Himself  both  the  end  and  the  source.  But  if  God 
thus  desires  Himself,  He  must  be  viewed  as  esse  intelligens;  in  fact, 
the  title  of  the  chapter  now  before  us  is  Quod  Deus  est  intelligens. 
To  put  this  into  modern  language  God  is,  upon  St.  Thomas'  view, 
self-conscious  and  self-objectifying  Eeason — Eeason  which  desires 
and  wills  itself ;  and  this  desiring  and  willing  of  itself  is  the  bringing 
into  being  of  the  world. 

Then,  in  further  developing  his  doctrine,  St.  Thomas  goes  on  to 
deal  more  at  length  with  the  self-knowledge  of  God.  God,  he  says, 
seipsum  perfecte  intelligit;1  furthermore  since  the  intelligible  form, 
quo  Deus  intelligit,  is  nothing  other  than  the  divine  essence  itself, 
therefore  God,  primo  et  per  se  solum  seipsum  cognoscit?  And  in 
the  theological  Summa,,  to  these  verbs  intelligo  and  cognosco  he  adds 
compreliendo : — Deus  perfecte  comprehendit  seipsum? 

Still  further,  the  knowledge  of  God  is  His  very  nature. 
Intelligere  Dei  est  sua  essential  or  as  the  theological  Summa  puts  it,5 

1  I.  47.  2  I.  48.  3  s.  T.  I.  14.  3.  *  I.  45.  5  I.  14.  4. 

336 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

[Ipsum]  intelligere  Dei  est  ejus  sulstantia.  This,  urges  St.  Thomas, 
follows  from  the  preceding.  God  is  esse  intelligens.  But  intelligere 
est  perfectio  et  actus  intelligentis. 

Thus,  then,  God  is  conceived  as  an  intelligence  that  knows,  that 
perfectly  comprehends,  itself.  And  this  character  as  intelligence  is 
the  essential  nature  of  God;  it  is  the  divine  substance  itself.  The 
view  of  Aquinas,  so  far,  might  be  summed  up  by  saying  that  to  him 
God  is  self-conscious,  self -determining,  self -objectifying  Reason:  self- 
conscious,  for  He  knows  Himself;  self-determining  and  self- 
objectifying,  for  He  determines  Himself  through  Himself,  is  to 
Himself  the  end  of  His  own  activities. 

This  brings  us  to  the  question  which,  for  the  purpose  of  our 
present  inquiry,  we  have  to  ask  concerning  the  Thomistic  Theism. 
It  has  been  our  task  to  trace  certain  elemental  oppositions  in  the 
field  of  philosophy  and  theology.  The  first  and  deepest  of  these  is 
that  between  the  negative  view — which,  in  religious  men,  becomes 
Mysticism — and  the  positive  view,  which,  when  it  enters  into  clear 
possession  of  its  highest  categories,  is  Idealism.  Those  highest 
categories  are  the  categories  involved  in  the  idea  of  spirit.  But  as 
we  have  seen,  even  when  these  have  been  gained,  there  is  still  possible 
a  more  abstract  and  a  more  concrete  use  of  them.  The  self-conscious 
and  self -determining  subject  of  the  world  may  be  viewed  as  in 
organic  connexion  with  the  whole  process  of  the  world;  not  merely 
of  certain  aspects  of  the  world  is  God  the  source,  but  of  the  whole 
order  of  the  world;  not  merely  through  some  fragment  of  it  is  He 
realising  His  purpose,  but  through  its  whole  process  and  history. 
Or,  again,  the  emphasis  may  be  put  so  entirely  upon  pure  reason  that 
the  sense-world  which  has  its  being  in  space  and  time  becomes  meta 
physically  a  hopeless  problem,  and  ethically  a  realm  to  be  withdrawn 
from.  Or  the  abstraction  may  be  carried  still  farther.  The  fact 
that  self-consciousness  and  the  objective  consciousness  are  correlative, 
that  consciousness  of  self  implies  consciousness  of  objects,  and  that 
without  such  consciousness  of  objects  there  is  no  such  thing  as  self- 
consciousness  : — this  may  be  forgotten,  and  the  emphasis  laid  alto 
gether  upon  the  mere  fact  of  self-consciousness,  upon  the  mere 
abstract  fact  that  "  I  am  I,"  upon  the  bare  "  I  think  "  that  attends 
23  337 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

each  fact  indifferently  without  reference  to  the  object  that  is  thought. 
Then  God  can  but  be  viewed  as  existing  in  the  blessedness  of  such  a 
self-contemplation  as  leaves  the  world,  in  some  inexplicable  way, 
apart  from  Him  and  alien  to  Him;  one  step  farther  in  the  way  of 
abstraction  would,  in  fact,  give  us  Mysticism.  These  are  the  three 
typical  possibilities  in  the  use  of  the  category  of  self-consciousness  as 
the  final  principle  of  explanation  of  the  world.  The  strife  between 
these — a  strife  often  implicit  and  unconscious — and  the  advance  from 
the  less  to  the  more  concrete,  make  up  the  inner  history  of  Idealism. 
And  the  failure  to  distinguish  them  clearly  is  the  source  of  some  of 
the  most  troublesome  difficulties  that  have  beset  Idealism  in  philosophy 
and  Theism  in  theology. 

In  what  position,  then,  does  St.  Thomas,  with  his  definite  enuncia 
tion  of  the  category  of  self-conscious  spirit,  stand  with  reference  to 
these  possible  types  ?  The  answer  to  this  we  have  now  to  trace. 

The  conclusion  of  St.  Thomas  just  noted  was  that  God  is  essen 
tially  intelligence;  intelligere  Dei  est  sua  essentia.  But  alongside 
this  we  have  at  once  to  set  two  other  conclusions.  The  first  is  a  con 
clusion  with  regard  to  the  nature  of  intelligence  which  involves  a 
view  of  the  relation  between  intelligence  and  its  objects.  "Intel 
ligere"  he  says,  "  is  the  activity  or  energising  (actus)  of  an  intel 
ligence — an  activity  which  exists  in  itself,  and  does  not  pass  over 
into  anything  extrinsic  to  it,  as,  for  instance,  heating  passes  over  into 
that  which  is  heated."1  This  definition  of  intelligere  at  once  raises 
the  vital  question  between  the  abstract  and  the  organic  view.  For 
the  definition  implies  that  whatsoever  God  knows  is  in  some  true 
sense  in  God.  Which,  then,  of  the  two  alternatives  will  St.  Thomas 
take?  If  he  wishes  to  separate  God  and  the  world  in  the  sense  of 
denying  that  the  relation  of  the  world  to  God  is  organic,  he  must 
deny  knowledge  of  the  world  to  God.  While  if  he  insists  that  God 
knows  the  world,  he  at  once  makes  the  world  intrinsic  to  God ;  makes 
the  world  the  objective  consciousness  of  God. 

What  he  does  is  to  assert  explicitly  and  strongly  that  God  knows 
the  world ;  but,  as  we  shall  find,  he  does  not  see — or  at  any  rate  does 

1  I.  45. 
338 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

not  draw — the  logical  consequence  which  this  assertion  carries  as 
soon  as  it  is  taken  together  with  his  own  conception  of  knowledge. 
God,  he  says.,  cognoscit  alia  a  se.1  For,  he  argues,  the  cognition  of 
an  effect  is  adequately  possessed  (sufficienter  hdbetur)  through  the 
cognition  of  its  cause.  Therefore,  since  God  is  through  His  own 
essence  the  causa  essendi  of  other  things,  and  since  He  most  fully 
knows  His  own  essence,  it  must  be  affirmed  that  He  etiam  alia 
cognoscat.  And  this  position  is  made  still  stronger  by  the  next 
chapter  which  declares  that  God  has  propriam  cognitionem  de  rebus 
omnibus?  And  with  this  propriam  cognitionem  de  rebus  omnibus 
Thomas  is  thoroughly  in  earnest.  In  several  chapters  both  in  the 
Contra  Gentiles  and  in  the  theological  Summa  he  expressly  affirms 
that  God  knows  the  things  which  are  not  ;3  He  knows  the  particular 
and  the  contingent;4  He  knows  the  infinite;5  He  knows  the  base  and 
the  evil.6  And  this  knowledge  of  God  which  includes  all  things,  and 
is  the  cause  of  things,  is  not  discursive;7  does  not  proceed  by  com 
pounding  and  dividing.8  On  the  contrary,  Deus  omnia  simul  intel- 
ligit,9  and  this  because  He  knows  all  things  una  specie  inteTligibili. 

If  we  put  these  two  views  together  we  at  once  have  the  positive 
tendency.  For  with  reference  to  all  things  that  are,  even  the  con 
tingent  and  the  evil,  with  reference  even  to  the  things  that  are  not, 
it  is  declared  that  God  omnia  simul  intelligit.  But  it  is  also  declared 
that  this  very  intelligere  is  "  the  activity  or  energising  of  an  intel 
ligence — an  activity  which  exists  in  itself  and  does  not  pass  over  into 
anything  extrinsic  to  it."  The  world  then  cannot  be  external  to 
God ;  the  disjunction  between  the  world  and  God  which  is  the  essence 
of  the  negative  tendency,  is  put  decisively  out  of  court;  the  world 
becomes  nothing  other  than  the  objective  consciousness  of  God. 

But  did  St.  Thomas  either  fully  accept,  or  consistently  keep 
himself  up  to,  this  point  of  view?  The  answer  is  that  in  part  he 
did,  in  part  did  not.  The  tendency  toward  the  more  concrete  view 

1 1.  49 :  cf .  Summa  Theol.  I.  14.  5,  6. 

2  Another  side  of  this  linking  together  of  the  divine  knowledge  and  the  things  of  the 
world  is  seen  in  the  principle  (argued,  e.g.,  in  Summa  Theol.  1. 14.  8)  that  scientia  (strictly 
speaking,  scientia  approbationis)  Dei  est  causa  rerum. 

31.  66;  S.  T.  I.  14.  9.  *  I.  67  ;  8.  T.  I.  14.  11  and  13.  *  I.  69 ;  S.  T.  I.  14.  12. 

«  I.  70,  71 ;  S.  T.  I.  14.  10.  7  I.  57  ;  S.  T.  I.  14.  7.  8  I.  58.  9  I.  55. 

339 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

is  found,  for  instance,  in  the  statement  that  God  is  in  all  things,  not 
as  though  each  thing  were  a  part  of  His  essence  (so  that  any  par 
ticular  thing  would  be  a  "  piece  "  or  "  mode  "  of  the  Divine  Being)  ; 
nor  as  an  accident;  but  as  the  mover  (agens)  is  present  in  that  which 
is  moved.  It  is  present,  again,  in  the  discussion  (found  in  each 
Summa)  in  which  it  is  pointed  out  that  the  videntes  Deum  per 
essentiam  would  see  all  things  in  God,  and  would  see  them  not  suc 
cessively  but  omnia  simul:1 — a  view  which  is  put  in  another  way 
when  it  is  said2  that  with  God  vivere  is  one  and  the  same  thing  with 
intelligere.  In  God  the  percept  and  the  thing  perceived  and  the  per 
ceiving  itself  are  the  same.  But  whatever  is  in  God  as  perceived  is 
his  life.  Wherefore,  since  all  things  which  are  made  by  God  are  in 
him  as  perceived  (intellecta) ,  it  follows  that  all  things  in  Him  are 
the  divine  life  itself.  Or  if  we  turn  to  the  later  Books  of  the  Contra 
Gentiles — references  to  the  Contra  Gentiles  have  so  far  been  to  the 
first  Book,  which  sets  forth  what  would  usually  be  called  St.  Thomas' 
"  conception  of  God  " — we  find  here  and  there  hints  which  look  in 
the  same  direction.  In  the  second  Book,  for  instance,  which  contains 
the  doctrine  of  creation,  he  insists,  in  dealing  with  the  diversities 
of  the  world,  that  the  distinction  of  things  from  one  another  is  not 
due  to  accident;  nor  is  matter  the  first  cause  of  it;3  nor  yet  con 
trariety  in  the  first  agents;  but  on  the  contrary,  multiplicity  and 
variety,  diversity  .and  inequality  in  created  things,  are  necessary,  that 
by  this  manifoldness  a  perfect  copy  of  the  divine  perfection  might 
be  found.4  In  the  third  Book,  whose  topic  is  in  part  Ethics  and  in 
part  the  questions  of  Providence — of  the  divine  government  and 
administration  of  the  world — it  is  asserted5  that  God  is  omnium 
finis,  that  to  know  God  (intelligere  Deum)  is  the  end  for  all  intel 
ligent  creatures6  (whence  it  follows  quod  ultima  hominis  felicitas 
non  sit  in  hac  vita)  ;7  that  to  all  operating  agents  God  is  the  cause 
of  their  operation  (so  that  every  operation  ought  to  be  ascribed  to 
God  as  to  the  first  and  principal  agent),8  and  yet  that  this  does  not 
exclude  free  will  in  the  part  of  the  creature  ;9  that  there  is  a  certain 
coincidence  of  natural  law  and  divine  law.10  In  the  fourth  Book, 

1  III.  59,  60;  £  T.  I.  12.  8  seq.  2  s.  T.  I.  18.  4.  3  II.  40. 

4  II.  45.  5  HI.  18.  6  HI.  25.  Tin.  48. 

8  III.  67.  9  III.  73.  10  III.  128  seq. 

340 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

which  is  given  to  the  consideration  of  revealed  truths,  we  come  to 
the  doctrine  of  the  Trinity.  But  to  that  reference  must  be  made  at 
a  later  point. 

Such  teachings  show  how  St.  Thomas  can  maintain  the  more 
concrete  point  of  view.  But  upon  the  whole  an  abstract  view  prevails; 
or  rather  the  rational  foundations  are  laid  for  the  concrete  view,  but 
hopeless  difficulties  intervene,  and  the  conclusion  which  is  finally 
drawn  is  to  a  very  considerable  extent  abstract.1 

The  difficulties  arise  both  from  the  side  of  the  world  and  from 
the  side  of  God.  From  the  side  of  the  world,  its  imperfection  stands 
over  against  the  eternal  and  changeless  perfection  of  God.  Metaphysi 
cally  the  world  is  imperfect,  as  a  divided  order  in  time  and  space. 
Ethically  it  is  imperfect,  as  the  seat  of  evil.  Hence  it  has  to  be  viewed 
as  in  some  sense  disjoined  from  God.  Yet,  as  the  doctrines  just 
referred  to  show,  St.  Thomas  sees  that  the  world  must  be  viewed  as 
intimately  in  connexion  with  God.  And  as  between  these  two 
necessities  what  he  does  is  to  adopt  something  like  a  Platonic  theory 
of  Ideas.  "  The  forms  which  exist  in  particular  things,"  he  says,  in 
that  very  chapter  of  the  Contra  Gentiles  whose  thesis  is  Quod  Deus 
est  intelligent,  "  are  imperfect."  But  everything  imperfect  is 
derived  from  something  perfect,  for  the  perfect  is  prior  in  nature  to 
the  imperfect,  just  as  actus  is  prior  to  potentia.  Hence  the 
imperfect  forms  which  exist  in  the  particular  things  of  the 
world,  must  be  derived  from  actually  subsisting  perfect  forms. 
And  these  can  subsist  only  in  an  intelligence.  To  St.  Thomas 
this  is  just  another  proof  that  God  is  esse  intelligens.  But  what 
concerns  us  here  is  that  it  really  shows  the  negative  tendency  at 
work.  Instead  of  the  order  of  this  world,  even  in  its  imperfections, 

i  One  result  of  this  contrasts  curiously  with  the  position  which  St.  Thomas  has  held, 
and  still  hold*,  as  the  guide  of  innumerable  churchmen:  in  following  the  standard  and 
master  of  orthodoxy,  we  must,  if  we  wish  to  keep  orthodox  ourselves,  be  careful  how  we 
go  beyond  what  stands  written  :  if  we  take  a  principle  from  one  place,  and  another  from 
another,  and  put  them  together,  and  adopt  the  conclusion  which  logically  follows,  we  are 
as  like  as  not  to  be  heretics.  As  an  exceedingly  keen-minded  teacher  of  philosophy,  to 
whom  I  am  greatly  indebted,  once  pointed  out,  when  St.  Thomas  (bv  reason  of  the  very 
clearness  and  sincerity  of  his  own  mind)  cannot  escape  doctrines  which  have  heretical 
implications,  he  gives  them  their  place  in  God,  but  forbids  them  to  us  men.  He  makes 
God  pantheistic,  but  he  will  not  let  us  be  pantheistic;  he  makes  God  heretical  to  save  our 
orthodoxy. 

341 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

being  regarded  as  wholly  organic  to  a  divine  purpose, — though  we 
men  cannot  clearly  see  how,  because  "  we  see  not  to  the  close  " — what 
is  really  asserted  is  that  there  are  two  worlds:  the  perfect  world  of 
ideal  forms,  which  exists  in  God,  or,  as  St.  Thomas  would  say,  in  the 
Word;  and  this  present  world  of  imperfection.  The  doctrine  of 
Ideas,  as  worked  out  in  the  greater  Bumma}  carries  the  same  impli 
cation;  though  it  is  limited  by  the  statement  that  evil  has  no  Idea 
in  God,  because  it  is  known  by  God  non  per  propriam  rationem  sed 
per  rationem  boni. 

That  which  intervenes  between  the  ideal  world  in  God,  and  this 
imperfect  world,  is  of  course  creation.  But  the  Thomistic  doctrine  of 
creation2  is  rather  a  repetition  of  the  doctrine  of  Ideas  than  an 
explanation  of  how  a  perfect  God  could  make  an  imperfect  world,  or 
how  the  imperfection  of  the  world  can  be  organic  to  the  accomplish 
ment  of  a  divine  purpose.  After  pointing  out  that  every  being  which 
in  any  way  whatsoever  exists,  is  of  God,  and  that  the  materia  prima 
is  created  by  God,  he  goes  on  to  discuss  the  question  whether  the 
formal  cause  (causa  exemplaris)  is  anything  beyond  God.  In  the 
opening  list  of  the  arguments  pro  and  contra  he  quotes  the  Augustin- 
ian  doctrine,  ideae  sunt  formae  principales,  quae  divina  intelligentia 
continentur,  to  prove  that  exemplaria  rerum  non  sunt  extra  Deum  and 
then  goes  on :  "I  give  the  obvious  answer :  God  is  the  prima  causa 
exemplaris  of  all  things.  And  as  evidence  of  this,  let  it  be  considered 
that  for  the  production  of  anything,  a  pattern  (exemplar)  is 
necessary,  that  the  effect  may  follow  a  determinate  form.  For  the 
artificer  produces  a  determinate  form  in  the  material  by  reason  of  a 
pattern  upon  which  he  looks,  whether  it  be  a  pattern  upon  which 
he  gazes  outwardly,  or  one  which  he  conceives  inwardly  in  his 
mind.  Moreover,  it  is  manifest  that  the  things  which  come  to  be 
in  the  course  of  nature  follow  determinate  forms.  This  determina 
tion  of  forms,  furthermore,  must  be  brought  back  to  the  divine 
wisdom  as  to  a  first  principle — to  the  divine  wisdom  which  has 
conceived  (excogitavit)  the  order  of  the  universe  which  consists  in  the 
distinction  of  things.  And  therefore  it  is  necessary  to  say  that  in  the 
divine  wisdom  are  the  rationes  omnium  rerum  which  we  have  above 

i  S.  T.  I.  15.  2  s.  T.  I.  44.  seg. 

342 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

called  (qu.  15.  art.  1)  Ideas,  that  is,  pattern  forms  (formas  exem 
plar  es)  existing  in  the  divine  mind."  Then  St.  Thomas  goes  on  to 
reconcile  this  with  the  doctrine  we  shall  have  presently  to  consider, 
that  of  the  simplicity  of  the  divine  nature;  and  comes  to  the  conclu 
sion  that  God  Himself  is  the  first  exemplar  of  all  things.  But  this,  it 
will  be  noticed,  still  leaves  the  disjunction.  The  ideal  world  exists  in 
God;  and  then  this  present  world  exists  somehow,  apart  from  that 
ideal  world,  as  an  imperfect  copy  of  it. 

But,  secondly,  there  were  difficulties  from  the  side  of  God.  St. 
Thomas,  with  the  medieval  theologians  generally,  is  committed  to  the 
doctrine  of  the  simplicity  of  the  divine  nature;  the  divine  nature  is 
such  a  unity  as  excludes  diversity.1  The  divine  nature,  St.  Thomas 
thinks,  must  be  such  a  unity,  because  else  it  would  be  a  compositum; 
and  that  for  many  reasons  is  impossible;  it  would  involve,  for 
instance,  the  possibility  of  dissolution,  and  then,  too,  omne  composi 
tum  posterius  est  suis  componeniibus? 

What  such  a  view  indicates  is  that  St.  Thomas,  even  in  formally 
declaring  that  God  is  self-conscious  and  self-determining  spirit,  has 
not  entered  into  the  real  significance  of  the  category  which  he  is  using. 
He  has  failed  to  apprehend  spirit  as  a  principle  of  synthesis,  of  unity 
in  diversity;  as  a  principle  whose  essential  nature  it  is  to  hold  many 
elements  together  in  the  unity  of  one  experience,  at  once  distinguish 
ing  itself  from  each  of  those  elements  and  each  of  them  from  one 
another.  But  so  to  conceive  spirit  is  the  key  to  the  whole  theistic 
view  of  the  world.  Continually  St.  Thomas  comes  near  to  such  a 
conception;  but  to  enter  clearly  upon  it,  and  to  lift  it  to  its  "full 
working  prerogative  "  as  a  principle  for  the  explanation  of  the  world, 
was  reserved  for  the  men  who  carried  forward  the  work  begun  by 
Immanuel  Kant.  So  that  St.  Thomas  is  exposed  to  a  great  danger. 
For  the  view  of  the  divine  nature  as  omnino  simplex,  if  carried  rigor 
ously  to  its  conclusion,  would  put  God  beyond  the  apprehension  of  our 
reason,  and  union  with  God  beyond  the  normal  capacities  of  our 

il.  18 ;  cf.  the  discussion  De  Unitate  Dei  in  the  greater  Summa  where  the  first  con 
clusion  is :  unum  non  addit  supra  ens  rein  aliquam,  sed  tantum  negationem  divisionis 
(S.  T.I.I}.  1). 

2  Et  dependent*  ex  eis  adds  the  theological  Summa  in  its  statement  of  these  reasons 
(I.  3.  7). 

343 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

nature.  That  is  to  say,  it  would  lead,  according  to  the  temper  of  the 
man  who  held  the  view,,  either  to  Agnosticism  or  to  Mysticism. 
Either  outcome  was,  of  course,  impossible  for  Aquinas ;  not  merely  on 
account  of  his  position  in  the  church,  but  by  reason  also  of  his  genuine 
'insight  into  the  positive  character  of  the  relation  of  God  to  the  world.1 
Yet  when  the  doctrine  of  the  simplicity  of  the  divine  nature  is  in  the 
foreground  of  his  thought,  he  can  save  himself  from  such  an  outcome 
only  by  ingenious  expedients.  Intellectus  nosier,  he  resolutely  affirms, 
de  Deo  simplici  non  in  vanum  enunciationes  format  componendo  et 
dividendo,  quamvis  Deus  omnino  sit  simplex.  It  is  true,  he  admits, 
that  we  come  to  knowledge  of  God  by  manifold  conceptions,  bonitas, 
sapientia,  and  the  like.  But  then,  he  urges,  we  do  not  attribute  the 
method  of  the  knowing  intellect  to  the  things  which  are  known — just 
as,  for  instance,  we  do  not  attribute  immateriality  to  a  stone,  although 
we  know  it  in  an  immaterial  fashion.  So,  then,  in  our  knowledge  of 
God,  the  manifoldness  of  conception  is  to  be  referred  to  ourselves,  as 
knowing  intellects,  but  unity  is  to  be  referred  to  the  God  who  is 
known. — Later,  when  St.  Thomas  has  affirmed  that  God  has  propriam 
cognitionem  de  rebus  omnibus,  the  same  difficulty  recurs.  If  the 
divine  intelligence  is  omnino  simplex,  how  can  there  be  in  it  multitudo 
intellectorum?  But  here  once  more,  instead  of  rising  to  the  view 
of  spirit  as  a  synthetic  principle,  and  therefore  a  principle  at  once  of 
unity  and  of  diversity,  St.  Thomas  saves  himself  by  an  ingenious 
device.  He  falls  back  upon  the  theory  of  intelligible  forms.  An 
intelligible  form  is  a  principium  formale  intellectualis  operationis;  by 
means  of  it  the  knowing  intelligence  knows  the  thing;  not  in  such  a 
way  that  the  knowing  itself  (intelligere  ipsum)  is  an  action  passing 
over  into  the  thing  known  (as  heating  "passes  over  into  the  thing 
heated  "" )  ;  but  in  such  a  way  that  the  knowing  remains  in  the 
intelligence,  and  yet  has  relation  to  the  thing  which  is  known.  But 
the  divine  intelligence  has  no  other  intelligible  form  than  its  own 
essence,  which  is  simple,  but  nevertheless  is  the  likeness  of  all  things. 
And  so,  by  one  intelligible  form  which  is  the  divine  nature,  and  by 

i  The  Mvst'c  outcome,  however,  ivas  possible  for  St.  Thomas'  fellow-Dominican  and, 
in  a  sense,  disciple,  Master  Eckhart. 

344 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

one  general  concept  (intentio  intellecta),  which  is  the  divine  Word, 
many  things  can  be  known  by  God.1 

We  have  already  seen  what  is  implied  in  St.  Thomas'  view  of  the 
activity  of  the  divine  intelligence  as  one  which  exists  in  itself  and 
does  not  pass  over  into  anything  extrinsic  to  itself.  Taken  in  con 
nexion  with  the  statement  that  God  has  propriam  cognitionem  de 
rebus  omnibus,  it  implies  that  the  world  is  in  God,  so  that  in  knowing 
the  world  God  is  not  going  beyond  Himself,  is  not  passing  over  into 
something  extrinsic  to  Himself.  But  what  we  have  just  seen  is  that 
from  both  sides — that  of  God,  that  of  the  world — Aquinas  is  led  to 
hold  the  two  apart.  And  this  is  rendered  easier  for  a  theologian  by 
another  fact.  In  the  genuine  order  of  science,  we  start  with  the  world 
of  our  experience,  and  seek  to  understand  it;  and  the  explanation  of 
it  we  find  at  last  in  God.  And  then,  of  course,  the  principle  of 
explanation  and  the  thing  explained  must  be  viewed  as  standing  in 
organic  connexion — unless,  as  sometimes  happens,  the  scientific 
inquiry  forgets  its  own  beginning.  But  if  you  start  with  ready-made 
conceptions — God,  the  soul,  the  world — you  feel  at  liberty  to  link 
these  together  or  hold  them  apart  as  the  exigencies  of  your  thought 
may  require.  And  thus  to  start  with  separate  ready-made  conceptions 
is  one  of  the  specific  dangers  of  the  professional  theologian;  it  is,  in 
fact,  the  essence  of  that  theological  procedure  known  as  the  dogmatic. 

But,  in  attempting  to  consider  how  far  the  Theism  of  Aquinas  is  pos 
itive  and  concrete,  how  far  abstract  and  negative,  we  have  still  another 
question  to  raise ;  and  that  the  central  one.  The  difficulties  which  we 
have  been  considering,  the  opposition  of  what  seem  to  be  necessities 
of  thought: — will  St.  Thomas  find  any  solution  for  these  when  he 
comes  to  deal  with  the  doctrines  of  the  Trinity  and  the  Incarnation? 
In  his  discussion  of  these,  if  anywhere,  we  may  expect  the  concrete 
view  to  come  fully  to  its  rights.  For  the  central  conception  of  the 
Christian  view  of  the  world  is  that  God  became  man,  and  that  thus 
there  was  lived,  under  the  actual  conditions  of  human  history,  a  life 
which  is  the  true  and  normal — in  the  strict  Platonic  sense,  the  ideal- 
human  life.  But  this  involves  a  thoroughly  concrete  view.  For  it 

i  I.e.  St.  Thomas  really  puts  the  two  sides  together  in  God  ;  the  diversities  are  put  into 
the  divine  nature,  which  is  nevertheless  declared  from  the  outset  to  be  a  unity  (see  Contra 
Gentiles,  I.  36,  46,  and  53). 

345 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

implies,  on  the  one  side,  that  God  fulfils  Himself  in  human  nature; 
and  on  the  other  side,  that  the  human  nature,  which  in  the  Son  of 
Man  rose  to  the  true  form  of  its  own  Idea,  is  potentially  the  divine 
nature.  Taking  the  discussion  in  the  Contra  Gentiles  with  that  in 
the  theological  Summa,  one  must  say,  however,  that  while  St.  Thomas 
advances  toward  such  a  view,  he  does  not  enter  fully  into  it.  Is  there 
a  procession  in  God?  he  asks.1  First,  he  notes  some  very  interesting 
counter-arguments.  For  instance,  (1)  procession  signifies  movement 
toward  the  outside,  but  in  God  there  is  nothing  movable  nor  extrane 
ous,  therefore  no  procession ;  ( 2 )  everything  which  proceeds  is  diverse 
from  that  from  which  it  proceeded.  But  in  God  there  is  no  diversity, 
but  the  completest  simplicity.  Therefore  in  God  there  is  no  proces 
sion.  But,  in  spite  of  these,  he  holds  that  there  is  a  procession  in  God. 
Not  as  a  cause  proceeding  into  its  effect;  that  would  give  us  the 
heresy  of  Arius.  Nor  as  a  cause  carrying  itself  into  its  effect  and 
impressing  its  own  likeness  thereupon;  that  would  be  the  opposite 
heresy,  the  error  of  Sabellius.  As  against  these  Thomas  holds  to  a 
procession  in  God;  such  as  appears  in  intelligence  whose  activity 
remains  in  itself  and  there  forms  a  concept — a  verbum  cordis,  of 
which  the  verbum  vocis  is  a  sign.  Such  a  procession,  urges  Thomas, 
there  is  in  God.  And  it  is  twofold — the  processio  Verbi,  which  can  be 
called  generatio  (generatio  Fili)  and  the  processio  amoris.  Then  he 
goes  on  to  distinguish  these,  the  one  (the  generation  of  the  Son) 
taking  place  secundum  actionem  intelligibilem,  the  other  (the  proces 
sion  of  the  Spirit)  secundum  operationem  voluntatis.  But  when  it 
comes  to  bring  the  Son,  and  the  Father  through  the  Son,  into  organic 
connexion  with  human  nature  and  with  all  the  breadth  of  the  human 
world,  the  great  monastic  Doctor  slackens  his  pace.  In  the  fourth 
Book  of  the  Contra  Gentiles2  he  does,  indeed,  bring  the  doctrine  of  the 
first  Book,  that  God  thinks  Himself,  into  relation  with  the  revealed 
doctrine  of  the  Word.  That  which  was  made  in  Him  was  life;  i.e., 
as  St.  Thomas  takes  it,  all  things  pre-existed  in  Him,  so  that  He  is 
both  the  Likeness  of  God  (habet  Deitatem,  et  est  verus  Deus,  imago 
invisibilis  Dei},  and  the  original  type  of  all  created  things.  But  this 
still  leaves  the  great  disjunction  possible ;  the  Word  is  the  Idea  of  all 

1  S.  T.  I.  27.  2  11.  8eq. 

34(5 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

things— but  yet  He  may  not  be  regarded  as  fulfilling  Himself  through 
all  things  and  realising  His  purpose  in  all  history.  In  fact,  one  is 
tempted  to  say  that  with  St.  Thomas,  as  with  so  many  later 
theologians,  the  other  elements  of  his  thought  govern  his  doctrine  of 
the  Trinity  and  the  Incarnation,  rather  than  the  doctrine  of  the 
Trinity  and  the  Incarnation  the  other  elements  of  his  thought. 

Such,  in  the  outline  of  its  logical  motives,  is  St.  Thomas7  concep 
tion  of  God.  So  limited  a  statement,  it  is  true,  does  not  do  justice 
to  the  Thomistic  Theism.  As  was  pointed  out  above,  if  justice  is  to 
be  done  to  any  man's  Theism — to  his  real  Theism,  which  may,  or  may 
not,  be  identical  with  his  professed — the  whole  body  of  his  thought 
must  be  taken  into  account.1  In  the  case  of  St.  Thomas  one  would 
have  to  consider,  in  particular,  how  genuinely  the  concrete  tendency 
comes  to  its  right  in  his  teleology :  in  his  view,  namely,  of  history  as 
the  process  of  the  realisation  of  a  divine  purpose;  and  of  the  state 
and  its  laws  as  factors  in  that  realisation. 

But  the  bare  logical  outline  now  before  us  is  enough  to  show  that 
within  the  system,  apparently  so  complete  and  full-rounded,  of  the 
great  Dominican  theologian,  there  is  a  deep  division  of  mind.  The 
dualism  can,  indeed,  almost  be  put  down  in  the  set  terms  of  an 
antimony.  The  thesis  is :  The  world,  as  a  single  system,  must  have 
come  from  God — the  Manichsean  view  simply  cannot  be  admitted. 
Therefore,  the  world  must,  in  the  last  analysis,  be  of  the  nature  of 
God;  i.e.,  must  be  essentially,  and  upon  the  whole,  good.  And  there 
fore  again,  in  some  way  which  is  difficult  or  impossible  for  the  human 
mind  in  its  present  state  to  comprehend,  the  imperfections  of  the  world 
must  be  organic  to  the  purposes  and  activity  of  the  divine  perfection ; 
and,  therefore,  still  farther,  the  world  is  a  true  home  and  field  of 
labour  for  the  sons  of  God,  and  the  normal  activities  that  make  up 
man's  life  in  this  world  are  man's  true  way  home  to  the  heavenly 
glory.  But  over  against  this  thesis  rises  the  antithesis:  The  world, 
as  it  stands,  is  manifestly  imperfect,  manifestly  evil.  Therefore,  it 
cannot  be  of  God;  and  consequently  cannot  be  a  true  home  or  arena 

i  It  is  no  rare  thing  for  a  church  teacher,  who  in  his  "  Theology  "  has  yielded  to  dualism 
—even  to  the  extent  of  Manichseism— to  show  himself  in  his  Ethics  and  Politics  a  sound 
ani  hearty  Theipt. 

347 


THE    THEISM    OF    ST.  THOMAS 

for  the  children  of  God;  so  that  man,  if  he  is  to  come  to  his  home  in 
God,  must  renounce  and  forsake  the  world. 

And  this  division  of  mind  is,  in  St.  Thomas,  no  mere  matter  of 
individual  thinking.  He,  under  the  form  of  a  theological  system,  as 
genuinely  as  Dante  under  the  form  of  poetry,  was  the  expression  of 
the  mind  of  the  Middle  Ages.  What  that  mind  was — its  strength 
through  devotion  to  God,  its  weakness  through  injustice  to  nature  and 
through  the  consequent  sundering  of  nature  and  grace — I  have  already 
attempted  to  indicate.1  Its  vision  of  the  glory  of  God  was  so  intense 
and  overmastering,  its  sense  of  the  evils  in  the  world  so  keen,  that  it 
was  driven  to  a  separation  of  the  divine  and  the  natural;  and  so  the 
very  man  who  in  modern  times  stood  for  its  spirit  of  systematic  com 
prehension,  could  rebuke  it  for  not  being  comprehensive  enough,  and 
could  say  of  it,  that  with  all  its  zeal  for  the  divine  it  made  the  divine 
kingdom  the  dwelling-place  of  the  dead,  attainable  only  through  the 
gate  of  death ;  and  the  natural  world  just  as  much  a  realm  of  death, 
for  there  is  no  divinity  in  it — God  being  outside  of  nature,  and  there 
fore,  nature  the  grave  of  God.-  The  charge  has  its  truth.  Yet 
gentler  words  would  be  still  closer  to  truth.  It  would  be  at  once  more 
kindly  and  more  wise  to  say  that,  as  a  matter  of  historical  fact,  when 
men  of  searching  intellect  and  pure  heart  have  dealt  with  the  actual 
life  of  the  world,  their  conclusions  have  fallen  in  two  directions  and 
approximated  to  two  types :  the  one  apprehends  God  as  the  eternal 
truth  and  life  of  the  world;  the  other  apprehends  Him  as  that  reality 
in  the  presence  of  which  the  world  fades  into  nothingness.  The 
spiritual  struggle  of  mediaeval  men  made  them  so  acutely  sensitive  to 
both  demands  that  in  their  thought  the  opposed  tendencies  lose  the 
sense  of  their  opposition,  and  are  interwoven.  In  Erigena  both  views 
are  present,  each  in  its  extremest  possible  form ;  but  with  the  positive 
taking  upon  the  whole  the  greater  place,  especially  at  the  close.  In 
St.  Thomas,  also,  both  views  are  present ;  but  they  stand  in  a  different 
'relation,  which  reminds  one  a  little  of  the  ground-lines  of  Plato's 
earlier  Idealism.  With  regard  to  the  "  real  "  world — the  world  which 

1  Supra,  pp.  29-33. 

2  Hegel,  History  of  Philosophy,  Eng.  tr.,  vol.  III.,  p.  94  seq.    It  is  the  scholastic  mind 
that  Hegel  has  specially  in  view. 

348 


CONCLUSION 

is  known  to  angelic  intelligences,  but  for  us  men  is  very  largely  a 
"  world  to  come  " — the  positive  or  Idealistic  view  prevails  completely ; 
while,  with  regard  to  the  world  "that  now  is,"  that  Idealism  is 
crossed  by  a  certain  measure  of  the  negative  or  abstract  view.  But  in 
spite  of  this  deep  division  of  the  mediaeval  mind,  in  spite  of  this 
distance  to  which  mediaeval  men  went  in  excluding  many  aspects  of 
the  world  and  of  our  life  from  genuine  reality,  we  must  in  fairness 
keep  open  eyes  for  the  fact  that  the  essential  spirit  of  mediaeval 
thought  was  the  spirit  of  unity  and  comprehension.  The  purpose  of 
the  mediaeval  mind  was  to  bring  all  human  knowledge  to  unity  in  a 
knowledge  of  God ;  and  if  this  attempt  was  partly  a  success,  partly  a 
failure,  alike  in  the  ninth  century  when  it  was  made  by  the  daring 
and  brilliant  mind  of  Erigena,  and  in  the  thirteenth  when  it  was 
undertaken  by  the  sober  and  massive  intelligence  of  St.  Thomas,  the 
reason  lies,  upon  a  last  view,  simply  in  this,  that  earth  is  not  heaven 
and  human  science  not  the  totum  simul  of  heavenly  vision. 


With  this  we  must  end  our  study  of  the  two  great  ways  in  which 
the  apprehension  of  God  has  shaped  men's  attitude  toward  the  world 
and  toward  their  own  life  in  the  affairs  of  the  world.  Mediaeval  men 
stood — where  all  men  stand — between  time  and  eternity;  and  it  was 
their  labour,  both  in  practice  and  in  speculation,  to  bring  their  life 
in  time  under  the  form  of  eternity.  They  felt  the  unity — the  unity  in 
God — of  all  existence.  Hence  the  inner  impulse  of  their  science  was 
to  see  the  world  as  one ;  and  to  see  it  as  one  by  knowing  God.  In  the 
light  of  the  knowledge  of  God  all  the  contending  elements  and 
currents  of  the  world  were  to  take  on  the  form  of  unity  and  eternity. 
But  the  material  of  which  their  life  was  made  defeated  that 

349 


CONCLUSION 

endeavour;  the  struggle  of  life  made  them  feel  precisely  the  hopeless 
dividedness  of  existence,  the  hopeless  irreconcilability  of  its  elements. 
They  had  fought  their  way,  with  infinite  toil  and  pain,  up  from  chaos ; 
with  infinite  toil  and  pain  were  subduing  the  flesh  to  the  spirit,  and 
the  passions  of  the  earth  to  heavenly  light.  God  and  the  world  stood 
for  them  far  asunder;  between  the  two  they  must  choose;  and  they 
chose  rather  to  lose  themselves  with  God  than  to  be  masters  of  the 
world.  As  a  man  sitting  in  the  midst  of  music  and  of  dreams  hears 
far  out  in  the  night  the  call  of  the  trumpet,  and  recognises  his  greater 
vocation,  and  turns  to  the  long  march  through  the  darkness,  and  to 
the  battle  that  with  its  chances  of  life  and  death  waits  the  break  of 
day;  so  the  leaders  of  mediaeval  religion  turned  from  the  allurements 
of  the  beautiful  and  terrible  world,  and  allowed  to  their  hearts  no 
love  save  the 'heavenly  love,1  and  gave  themselves  to  the  one  task  of 
so  organising  society  that  it  should  be,  in  labour,  in  discipline,  in 
vision,  a  training-school  for  the  life  to  come.  So  that  the  final  insight 
to  which  both  their  life  and  their  science  led  them,  defeated  in  part 
the  impulse  with  whicli  their  science  began.  All  things  of  the  world  are 
one  in  God;  and  therefore  to  know  the  world  as  it  truly  is  we  must 
know  God.  But  so  soon  as  we  come  to  a  knowledge  of  God,  we  come 
to  that  which  condemns  the  world.  Through  all  things  there  runs 
the  absolute  and  final  distinction  between  God  and  that  which  is  not 
God,  between  heaven  and  the  awful  eternity  of  hell.  And  man,  as  he 
looks  upon  God  and  upon  that  twofold  issue  of  his  own  life,  stands  in 
a  strait  with  regard*  to  all  the  things  of  this  world  and  all  the  appeal 
which  they  make  to  his  heart.  We  must  love  God;  but  whether  we 
can  love  Him  in  loving  the  things  which  He  has  made  is  a  problem 
of  hopeless  difficulty;  for  the  things  which  He  has  made  have  some 
how  come  to  be  full  of  evil.  On  the  one  hand,  there  is  no  source  of 
real  existence  but  God;  and,  therefore,  throughout  the  whole  of 
existence,  with  all  its  trouble  and  toil  and  darkness — its  "  desperate 
and  hideous  years/'  its  "  wrong  too  bitter  for  atoning  " — God  must 
be  achieving  a  vast  design.  But  on  the  other  hand,  the  world  is  evil 

1  If  we  turn  from  Aquinas  to  Dante,  the  fact  remains  that,  while  Dante's  love  never 
loses  its  humanity,  it  maintains  itself  only  by  lifting  itself  from  earth  to  heaven.  The 
Beatrice  whom  Dante  loved  through  all  his  greater  years  was  the  Beatrice  who,  among 
the  blessed,  looked  upon  the  face  of  God. 

350 


CONCLUSION 

while  God  is  good ;  therefore,  the  world  is  alien  to  God,  and  the  sons 
of  God  must  renounce  it.  Such  was  the  problem  laid  upon  mediaeval 
men  by  that  wisdom  which  is  the  inner  soul  of  the  ages,  the  wisdom 
which  allots  to  each  mortal  generation  its  toil,  and  leads  each  by  the 
burden  of  hopeless  difficulties  into  a  citizenship  of  eternity.  With 
that  problem  mediaeval  men  did  the  best  that  they  could  do:  they 
admitted  both  solutions  to  a  place  in  their  thought,  and  became  at 
once  Idealists,  serving  God  by  mastering  the  world,  and  Mystics, 
finding  God  by  renouncing  both  the  world  and  their  own  individuality. 
For  modern  men  the  problem  of  life,  however  different  in  appear 
ance,  is  not  different  in  essence.  On  the  one  side,  for  us  as  for  them, 
stands  the  evil  of  the  world.  And  its  distinctively  modern  form — the 
industrial  and  social  selfishness  which  allows  whole  classes  of  human 
beings  to  live  here  upon  the  earth  in  hell — is,  with  all  its  refinement, 
a  profounder  form  of  evil  than  that  savage  power  of  the  flesh  which 
medieval  men  had  to  overcome,  as,  in  obedience  to  a  light  from 
heaven,  they  lifted  themselves  out  of  their  northern  barbarism.  But 
if  that  which  shows  the  world  as  divided  and  broken  has  taken  on  an 
intenser  form,  so  also  has  the  demand  for  unity ;  the  demand,  namely, 
that  the  world  shall  be  seen  as  one  order  of  existence  framed  through 
out  for  the  realisation  of  one  supreme  purpose;  and  that,  therefore, 
all  the  interpretations  of  the  world,  scientific,  moral,  religious,  shall 
lead  to  a  common  centre.  This  demand  arises  from  all  sides  of  the 
modern  situation;  alike  from  the  scientific  side,  and  from  the 
religious  and  moral.  For  science  can  admit  no  dualism;  at  every 
point  in  its  work  it  presupposes  and  implies  the  unity  of  all  existence, 
and  the  continuity  of  the  whole  cosmic  process,  including  man  and 
all  that  makes  up  man's  life.  While  theology  (and  still  more  the 
religion  of  which  theology  is  the  intellectual  expression  or  shadow) 
with  its  central  presupposition  of  the  supremacy  of  God,  just  as  truly 
demands  the  unity  of  all  existence  and  the  continuity  of  the  whole 
process  of  the  universe ;  and  that  whether  we  interpret  the  supremacy 
of  God  in  Christian  and  paternal  terms,  or  in  Roman  and  forensic. 
And  the  moral  consciousness,  which  seems  most  of  all  to  force  a 
dualistic  belief  upon  the  pure  heart  and  the  upright  spirit,  really 
calls  for  an  ultimate  unity.  As  Plato  saw,  the  Chief  Good  must  be 

351 


CONCLUSION 

one,  and  it  must  be  the  supreme  principle  of  Being.  It  must  be  the 
highest  principle  of  the  whole  system  of  existence  as  well  as  of  man's 
moral  endeavour.  For  in  the  last  analysis  the  Good  for  man  must  be 
the  divine  nature;  and  for  the  attainment  of  it — the  genuine  and 
difficult,  not  the  easy  and  fictitious,  attainment  of  it — the  whole  order 
of  the  world  must  be  framed. 

In  some  respects,  modern  thought,  with  all  its  dividedness,  is  in  a 
better  position  than  medieval  to  meet  that  demand.  For  one  thing, 
we  have  a  keener  sense  of  the  difficulty  of  the  task.  Mediaeval  men 
boldly  attempted  to  unify  reason  and  faith,  science  and  revelation. 
But  if  we  moderns  are  acutely  conscious  of  any  one  thing  more  than 
of  any  other,  it  is  that  such  unification  must  be  achieved,  if  at  all,  in 
some  greater  experience  to  come  ubi  ipsa  veritas  vita  animae  nostrae 
erit.  We  are  content  to  speak,  not  of  unifying,  but  of  reconciling. 
Anything  that  could  fairly  be  called  the  unification  of  science  and 
revelation  would  require  completed  (i.e.,  eternal)  science,  completed 
revelation,  and  complete  intellectual  vision  ;  whereas  we  ourselves,  and 
our  science,  and  our  revelation  (so  far  as  revelation  means  something 
apprehensible  by  the  human  spirit),  are  all  alike  incomplete  in  the 
sense  of  existing  under  the  form  of  time.  But  we  can  seek  to  recon 
cile  with  each  other  the  two  great  powers  which  make  up  our  spiritual 
life — the  scientific  reason  which  sees  the  world  as  an  order  of 
continuity  and  changeless  law,  and  the  religious  spirit  which 
organises  life  in  accordance  with  a  faith  in  God: — to  reconcile  these 
in  a  reasoned  belief  that  the  world  is  a  divinely-ordered  system  and 
its  history  a  divinely-guided  process.1  Then,  too,  for  men  who  see 
things  as  they  are,  the  steady  advance  of  science  and  its  strengthen 
ing  of  its  own  position  bring  hope  rather  than  fear.  The  man  who 
sees  nature  as  an  order  of  unchanging  law,  is  better  qualified  to 
advance  to  the  view  that  the  cosmic  process  is,  in  constitution  and 
purpose,  divine  and  divinely  rational,  than  is  the  man  who  sees  that 

i  It  should  be  understood  that,  if  men  of  science  have  a  difficulty  in  admitting  this 
belief,  theologians  have  a  still  greater  difficulty  in  holding  it  consistently.  The  intel 
lectual  pressure  upon  a  theologian  is  a  terrible  one ;  and  the  clearer  his  mind  the  more 
terrible  the  pressure.  Faith  in  God,  and  the  fact  of  evil,  constitute  when  taken  together 
tho  last  and  most  awful  of  all  the  problems  by  which  the  human  mind  is  tried.  The 
theologian  is  always  exposed  to  the  temptation  to  be  a  Theist  toward  his  opponents,  but  a 
Manichsean  within  his  own  system. 

352 


CONCLUSION. 

process  as  subject  to  arbitrary  divine  fiats  (a  view  which  implies  that 
the  ordinary  process  of  the  world  goes  its  own  way  upon  some  non- 
divine  level,  but  subject  to  interference  from  above).1  Science  and 
religion,  in  fact,  by  doing  justice  to  themselves,  enter  into  deeper 
kinship  with  each  other.  Or  perhaps  it  would  be  more  accurate  to 
say  that  religion,  since  it  includes  the  whole  of  life,  can  never  do 
justice  to  itself  without  taking  up  into  itself  the  spirit  of  science. 
And,  to  some  extent,  that  is  being  done  to-day.  Theology,  for 
example,  is  being  transformed  by  a  genuinely  scientific  study  of  the 
religious  experiences  and  types  of  mind  recorded  in  the  Bible,  and 
specially  of  that  mind  of  Jesus  which  is  at  once  the  fulfilment  and  the 
illumination  of  those  experiences;  and,  as  so  transformed,  is  becom 
ing  less  and  less  a  declaration  made  on  the  authority  of  the  church, 
and  more  and  more  an  expression  of  the  facts  of  actual  life,  and  of 
the  faiths  involved  in  those  facts. 

So  that  on  the  intellectual  side  the  situation  certainly  grows  more 
hopeful  age  by  age.  But  in  the  world  of  to-day  that  which  stands 
darkly  in  the  way  is  a  fact  of  another  order.  It  is  not  a  fact  arising 
from  the  essential  relations  between  the  scientific  and  the  religious 
mind.  It  has  really  little  to  do  with  any  conflict  between  the 
scientific  spirit  and  the  spirit  of  the  organised  church,  or  between  the 
scientific  principle  of  continuity  and  all  that  love,  all  those  hopes  and 
visions,  which  have  in  the  heart  of  man  a  natural  temple.  The  seat 
of  it  is  in  the  temper  with  which  we  live  the  practical  life.  Mediaeval 
men  were  so  intent  upon  God  that  they  saw  Him  in  and  for  Himself, 
but  did  not  with  sufficient  clearness  see  Him  in  the  ordinary  and  the 
everyday,  in  the  phenomena  of  nature,  in  the  layman's  life.  But  we, 
throughout  our  whole  organisation  of  commerce  and  society,  have  so 
given  ourselves  to  ourselves  that  we  do  not  like  to  keep  God  in  our 
thoughts  at  all.  In  a  social  and  industrial  order  where  the  weak  serve 
the  successful  we  labour  proudly  and  masterfully,  each  man  seeking 
by  "  length  of  watching,  strength  of  mind  "  to  build  a  city  for  him 
self.  It  is  hard  for  us  to  give  ourselves  to  God,  and  to  citizenship  in 
the  city  where  there  is  no  selfishness,  no  impoverishing  or  crippling 
of  one  life  to  maintain  the  splendour  of  another,  but  the  good  that 

i  Cf-  supra,  pp.  195-198;  cf.  p.  53,  note. 
24  353 


CONCLUSION. 

all  men  serve  is  a  common  good.  And  this  habit  of  living  each  for 
himself  is  not  only  the  source  of  innumerable  and  cruel  evils ;  it  even 
infuses  a  soul  of  evil  into  the  very  activities  which,  if  performed  as 
unto  God,  would  be  a  fulfilment  of  His  purpose. 

By  this  it  is  not  meant  that  we  modern  men  can  save  ourselves 
from  ourselves  only  by  returning  to  the  mediaeval  position.  Still  less 
is  it  meant  that  we  can  save  ourselves  from  the  lower  world  which 
is  too  much  with  us,  only  by  turning  back  to  that  ancient  theology 
before  whose  overmastering  vision  of  God  the  world  faded  into 
nothingness  as  dreams  fade  at  break  of  day.  On  the  contrary,  we  can 
save  ourselves  only  by  being  true  to  that  greater  world  which  we 
have  discovered  and  made  our  own.  But  what  such  fidelity  to  the 
world  really  involves  depends  upon  what  the  world  is.  And  the  truth 
of  the  world,  the  truth  both  of  ourselves  and  of  the  world,  is  God; 
God,  and  that  "  far-off  divine  event "  which  is  the  purpose  of  God, 
are  the  meaning  of  the  world.  And  this  means  that  the  citizenship 
to  which  we  are  called  is  a  heavenly  citizenship;  but  it  also  means 
that  that  heavenly  citizenship  must  first  be  fulfilled  upon  the  earth,  in 
the  life  in  which  our  duties  are  those  of  the  good  neighbour,  the 
honest  citizen,  the  devoted  churchman.  The  perfection  of  human  life 
lies  in  being  at  one  with  God ;  but  to  that  oneness  with  God  men  can 
come,  not  by  departure  from  the  world  into  eternal  quietude,  but 
only  by  flinging  themselves  into  the  labours  and  causes  of  the  history 
in  which  God  is  realising  His  eternal  purpose.  The  true  inspiration 
of  a  man's  life  is  the  love  of  God,  its  true  object  the  glory  of  God; 
but  that  glory  is  one  of  work  and  of  struggle  rather  than  of  silent 
peace.  "We  have  much  to  learn  from  the  mystic  saint  in  the  loneliness 
of  his  rest  in  God.  But  his  securely-guarded  peace  is  not  for  us. 
Even  while  we  honour  him,  we  must  turn  our  faces  toward  a  life  at 
once  more  commonplace  and  more  divine.  The  man  to  whom  the  love 
of  God  is  the  central  impulse  of  life  must  take  his  place  in  the  world, 
must  share  in  its  labours  and  duties  and  affections  and  losses,  must 
undergo  the  fate  which  it  has  for  all  its  citizens.  And  that  fate  is 
seldom  a  light  one.  They  who  in  the  manifold  relationships  of  life 
and  in  the  affairs  of  the  world  seek  to  be  faithful  to  God  and  man,  are 
likely  to  come  at  last  before  God  bearing  deep  marks  of  toil  and 

854 


CONCLUSION. 

storm;  like  ships  that  within  them  carry  high  and  gentle  hearts,  but 
can  look  for  no  escape  from  the  dangers  that  are  native  to  the  sea, 
and  come  at  last  to  harbour  weather-beaten,  scarred  by  lightning  and 
tempest  and  hidden  rock.  To  many — and  they  are  not  the  forgotten 
of  God — is  not  given  the  life  of  those  who  dwell  here  upon  the  earth 
in  great  peace,  looking  upon  God,  and  in  all  the  fierce  storm  of  the 
world  seeing  nothing  but  God.  Most  of  us  labour  with  a  more 
troubled  blending  of  anguish  and  calm,  of  remorse  and  hope,  toward 
our  west.  But  when  the  light  of  day  is  passing  from  the  sky,  and 
through  the  shadow  there  begins  to  break  that  other  light  of  the  stars 
from  their  infinite  spaces,  and  the  worn  hands  that  have  laboured 
hard  in  the  world's  affairs  begin  to  stretch  themselves  out  "  for  love  of 
the  farther  shore,"  then  the  man  as  he  turns  to  the  untravelled  world 
which  awaits  him  across  the  darkness  may  know  at  least  this :  already 
in  this  world  he  has  had  his  part  in  the  realisation  of  a  purpose  of 
God ;  and  in  the  world  to  come  that  which  waits  for  him,  and  for  his 
fellows,  and  for  all  the  human  struggle,  is  not  less  of  God,  but  more. 


355 


INDEX. 


Agnosticism,  4,  344. 

Apologists,  the,  272. 

Aquinas,  see  St.  Thomas. 

Areopagite,  the,  see  Dionysius. 

Aristotle,  7,  58,  59,  60,  90,  220,  253-259,  260,  261,  267,  294,  302,  303,  304,  308,  335. 

bar  Sudaili,  Stephen,  273. 

Boethius,  97w. 

Bradley,  F.  H.,  219w#,  233n. 

Calvinism  and  Arminianism,  79». 

Cause,  the  conception  of,  as  used  by  Spinoza,  172. 

Creation,    must   begin   with   something   less   than   perfection,    242,  258,  303,  308. 

Cf.  82  *eq. 
Cudworth,  88w. 

Dante,  310,  350n. 

Descartes,  59,  114,  154-158,  159,  160,  161,  193,  219,  271. 

Dionysius  the  Areopagite,  273,  277,  279,  287,  289,  290,  291. 

Eckhart,  Master,  147,  164,  165,  219,  344?i. 
Erigena,  14,  220,  267,  271-331,  348. 

Freedom  and   Necessity,  78,  79   (with  note  2),    102-105,  178  (with  note  2),  179. 
—in  Spinoza,  183,  184. 

Goethe,  198n. 

Green,  T.  H.,  8,  26?*,  63,  64. 

Hegel,  52,  60-63,  90,  114,  194,  195,  301,  312,  330,  331,  348. 
Herder,  198. 
Hierotheus,  273. 
Hume,  59n,  113,  114. 

Idealism 

—compared  with  Mysticism,  7-12,  83n,  115-122,  287n. 

—the  types  of,  Abstract  and  Concrete,  12,  225,  227,  231,  232,  233,  235,  238-247, 

251-263,  265,  266,  335,  337,  338-349,  350,  351. 
—of  Aristotle,  253-259. 
—of  Christianity,  262-266. 

—of  Erigena,  see  271-331,  but  specially  310-312,  316  aeq.,  327-331. 
—of  Plato,  203-247. 
— in  Spinoza,  see  176-195. 
— the  Idealistic  position  outlined,  17- HO. 

357 


INDEX 

Kant,   2,  46,  59,  93,  114,  125,  126,  180,  194,  195,  219,  220,  267,  342. 

Manichasism,  70/»,  99,  221,  266,  307,  319,  347 n,  352n. 

Materialism,  4,  38,  39,  47,  53«. 

Maximus  the  Confessor,  273,  291,  323,  328. 

Mediaeval  view  of  the  world,  29-34;  see  also  Erigeua,  Mysticism,  St.  Thomas. 

Mysticism 

—compared  with  Idealism,  7-12,  S3?i,  115-122,  287n. 

—in  Parmenides,  126,  127-132,  217. 

—Hindu,  126,  132-141,  217. 

— Neo-Platonic,  126,  141-144,  272-274;  and  see  Plotinus. 

—Mediaeval,  126,  145-150,  162,  217-219 ;  and  see  Erigena. 

—Modern,  151,  152. 

—in  Spinoza,  115,  116,  152-165. 

—in  Plato,  58,  124,  125,  214-232,  236. 

—in  Erigena,  see  271-331. 

Necessity,  see  Freedom. 

Neo-Platonism,  see  Mysticism  and  Plotinus. 

Newman,  J.  H.,  17-23,  27,  28,  32,  50,  53,  73,  75. 

Origen,  SOw,  88n,  292,  319,  321. 

Pantheism,  287w,   311  ;  and  see  Spinoza  and  Erigena. 

Parmenides,  59n,  126,  128-131,  135,  136,  152,  157>i,   159,   161,   162,  217    236    285 

Of.  140,  147. 
Plato,  2,  7,  11,  13,  25,  46,  57,  58,  59,  93,  94w,  96  (with  note),  108,  109,  124,  125,  203- 

247,  251-253,  255,  256,  257w,  258,  259,  260,  267,  272,  285,  294,  301,  302,  303, 

304,  307,  308,  317,  335,  348,  351. 
Plotinus,  142-144,  175,  284-286,  291,  292,  297,  298,  301,  312. 

Renaissance,  the,  35,  59. 
Koyce,  204,  213w& 

St.  Thomas,  14,  40,  90,  145,  175rc,  220,  267,  335-349. 
Spinoza,  59,  113-199,  219,  220,  267,  271,  286,  330,331. 
Stevenson,  R.  L.,  317. 
Stoics,  253,  260,  261. 

Wordsworth,  23-29,  32,  50,  53,  74,  75,   lOOn,  198«. 


358 


" 


_CWB— '.    Ott* 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY 


Philos       31ev/ett,   George  John 

The   study  of  nature  and 
the  vision  of  God