Skip to main content

Full text of "Thomas Hobbes"

See other formats


2 

PHILOSOPHIES  ANCIENT  AND  MODERN 


THOMAS    HOBBES 


NOTE 

As  a  consequence  of  the  success  of  the  series  of  Religions 
Ancient  and  Modern,  Messrs.  CONSTABLE  have  decided  to  issue 
a  set  of  similar  primers,  with  brief  introductions,  lists  of  dates, 
and  selected  authorities,  presenting  to  the  wider  public  the 
salient  features  of  the  Philosophies  of  Greece  and  Home  and  of 
the  Middle  Ages,  as  well  as  of  modern  Europe.  They  will 
appear  in  the  same  handy  Shilling  volumes,  with  neat  cloth 
bindings  and  paper  envelopes,  which  have  proved  so  attractive 
in  the  case  of  the  Religions.  The  writing  in  each  case  will  be 
confided  to  an  eminent  authority,  and  one  who  has  already 
proved  himself  capable  of  scholarly  yet  popular  exposition 
within  a  small  compass. 

Among  the  first  volumes  to  appear  will  be  : — 

Early  Greek  Philosophy.     By  A.  W.  BENN,  author  of  The  Philo 
sophy  of  Greece,  Rationalism  in  the  Nineteenth  Century. 

Stoicism.     By  Professor  ST.  GEORGE  STOCK,  author  of  Deduc 
tive  Logic,  editor  of  the  Apology  of  Plato,  etc. 

Plato.     By  Professor  A.  E.  TAYLOR,  St.  Andrews  University, 
author  of  The  Problem  of  Conduct. 

Scholasticism.     By  Father  RICKABY,  S.  J. 

Hoboes.    By  Professor  A.  E.  TAYLOR. 

Locke.     By  Professor  ALEXANDER,  of  Owens  College. 

Comte  and  Mill.     By  T.   W.   WHITTAKER,    author    of    The 
Neoplatonists,  Apollonius  of  Tyana  and  other  Essays. 

Herbert  Spencer.     By  W.  H.  HUDSON,  author  of  An  Intro 
duction  to  Spencer's  Philosophy. 

Schopenhauer.     By  T.  W.  WHITTAKER. 

Berkeley.     By  Professor  CAMPBELL  FRASER,  D.C.L.,  LL.D. 

Bergsen.    By  Father  TYRRELL. 


THOMAS    HOBBES 


By 
A.    E.   TAYLOR 


LONDON 
.RCHIBALD  CONSTABLE  &  CO  LTD 

1908 


B 
IU7 


PREFATORY    NOTE 

THIS  brief  sketch  has  throughout  been  written  directly  from 
the  original  text  of  Hobbes  himself  and  his  contemporary 
biographers,  though  use  has,  of  course,  been  made,  especially 
in  the  first  chapter,  of  the  labours  of  such  modern  students  as 
Professor  Croom  Kobertson,  Professor  F.  Tonnies,  and  Sir 
Leslie  Stephen.  The  verbal  quotations  from  Hobbes's  works 
are  given  from  the  following  editions  :  (1)  Elements  of  Philo 
sophy,  (Concerning  Body},  London,  1656  ;  (2)  Human  Nature 
and  De  Corpore  Politico,  from  the  third  edition  of  Hobbes's 
Tripos,  London,  1864  ;  (3)  Leviathan,  from  the  reprint  of  the 
first  edition  in  the  series  of  '  Cambridge  English  Classics,'  1904, 
which  has  been  carefully  compared  with  my  own  copy  of  the 
edition  of  1651,  (apparently  one  of  the  '  inferior  '  issue).  The 
spelling  of  these  editions  has  been  preserved,  but  the  punctua 
tion  modified  in  accord  with  present-day  usage.  Allusions 
to  the  Latin  texts  of  (1)  and  (3)  are  based  on  the  edition 
of  Hobbes's  Opera  Philosophica  published  by  Blaeuw  of 
Amsterdam  in  1668. 

A.  E.  TAYLOR. 


CONTENTS 

CHAP.  PAGE 

i.  LIFE, 1 

ii.  PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE SAND  METHODS,       .        .  27 

in.  EMPIRICAL  PSYCHOLOGY — THE  NATURE  OF  MAN,  55^" 
iv.  THE  MAKING  OF  THE  LEVIATHAN,       .        .  ^f    76   "~~ 

v.  THE  POWERS  OF  THE  SOVEREIGN,"*        .        .        .  10^^- 

vi.  CHURCH  AND  STATE, -T  116 

CONCLUSION, 124 

BOOKS  USEFUL  TO  THE  STUDENT  OF  HOBBES,      .  127 


vii 


THOMAS     HOBBES 
CHAPTER    I 

LIFE 

THE  long  life  of  Thomas  Hobbes  covers  almost 
the  whole  of  the  most  critical  period  alike  in  the 
growth  of  modern  science  and  in  the  development 
of  the  British  Constitution.  Born  in  the  year  of 
the  Armada,  Hobbes  did  not  die  until  nine  years 
before  the  great  Revolution  which  finally  deter 
mined  the  question  whether  the  British  Islands 
should  be  ruled  constitutionally  or  absolutely. 
He  lived  through  the  Stuart  attempt  to  convert 
England  into  an  absolute  monarchy,  the  Puritan 
revolution  and  great  Civil  War,  the  political  and 
ecclesiastical  experiments  of  the  Long  Parliament 
and  of  Cromwell,  the  restoration  of  the  exiled 
line,  and  the  beginnings  of  modern  Whiggism  and 
Nonconformity.  Still  more  remarkable  were  the 
changes  which  came  over  the  face  of  science 
during  the  same  period.  When  Hobbes  entered 
A  i 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

the  University  as  a  lad,  the  sham  Aristoteliar 
of  the  Middle  Ages  was  still  officially  taught  ii 
lecture-rooms ;  before  he  died,  mechanical  sci€ 
had  been  placed  on  a  secure  footing  by  Kef 
Galileo,  and   Descartes,   the   foundations   of 
scientific    study   of  physiology   and    magneti 
had  been  laid  by  Harvey  and  Gilbert,  the  Ho 
Society  for  experimental  research  into  nature  1 
been  incorporated  for   more  than  a  generatic 
analytical  geometry  had  been  created  by  Descart 
and  the  calculus  by  Leibniz  and  Newton,  wh 
it  was  only  eight  years  after  his  death  that  t 
final  exposition  of  the  new  mechanical  conceptii 
of  the  universe  was  given  by  Newton's  Principi 
It  is  only  natural  that  a  philosopher  who  w 
also  a  keen  observer  of  men  and  affairs,  livir 
through  such  a  period  of  crisis,  should  have  mac 
the  most  daring  of  all  attempts  to  base  the  whoi 
of  knowledge   on   the   principles   of  mechanic! 
materialism,  and  should   also  have  become   th 
creator  of  a  purely  naturalistic  theory  of  ethic 
and  sociology. 

Thomas  Hobbes,  the  second  son  of  the  Yicar  o 
Westport,  now  included  in  the  town  of  Malmes 
bury  in  Wiltshire,  was  prematurely  born  on  Gooc 
Friday,  April  5,_jj88L  His  own  theory  wa; 
that  both  his  premature  birth  and  his  constitu 


LIFE 

tional  timidity  were  consequences  of  his  mother's 
alarm  at  the  impending  approach  of  the  Great 
Armada.  The  father,  'one  of  the  ignorant  Sir 
Johns  of  Elizabeth's  time,'  fell  into  trouble  by 
assaulting  a  rival  cleric  at  the  church  door,  and 
was  obliged  to  go  into  hiding,  but  the  boy's  edu 
cation  was  cared  for  by  a  maternal  uncle,  who  was 
a  flourishing  glover  and  alderman  of  Malmes- 
bury.  After  a  period  of  preliminary  schooling  at 
Malmesbury  and  Westport,  where  he  learned 
enough  of  the  classical  languages  to  translate 
Euripides'  Medea  into  Latin  verse  at  the  age  of 
fourteen,  the  lad  was  sent  to  Oxford,  where  he 
was  entered  at  Magdalen  Hall,  then  an  important 
centre  of  Puritanism.  It  was  a  time  of  general 
relaxation  of  university  discipline,  and  the  acri 
monious  attacks  made  by  Hobbes  in  later  life  on 
the  English  Universities  as  haunts  of  debauchery, 
hotbeds  of  disloyalty,  and  places  where  the 
elements  of  Mathematics  and  Physics  were 
unknown,  must  have  been  chiefly  based  on  his 
undergraduate  experiences.  He  tells  us  hi  iself 
of  the  contempt  he  conceived  for  the  traditional 
a  iholastic  logic  and  physics  expounded  by  his 
tutors,  and  of  the  joy  he  felt  in  escaping  from 
their  lectures  to  the  bookshops  where  he  could 
pore  over  books  of  travel  and  maps,  and  follow 

3 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

in  imagination  the  voyages  of  the  great  Eliza 
bethan  buccaneers. 

This  rather  unprofitable  period  of  University 
life  ended,  after  five  years,  when  Hobbes  graduated 
Bachelor  of  Arts  on  February  5,  160|."^-Tm- 
mediately  afterwards  he  formed  what  was  to 
prove  a  lifelong  and  honourable  connection  with 
the  rising  family  of  Cavendish.  William  Caven 
dish,  Baron  Hardwick  (afterwards  Earl  of  Devon 
shire),  second  son  by  her  second  marriage  of  the 
famous  '  Bess  of  Hardwick/  being  anxious  to  find 
a  suitable  companion  and  tutor  for  his  eldest 
son,  offered  the  post  to  Hobbes  on  the  recom 
mendation  of  the  then  President  of  Magdalen 
Hall.  By  all  accounts  Hobbes's  actual  services 
seem  to  have  been  those  of  companion  rather 
than  tutor.  Young  Mr.  Cavendish  was  a  decided 
spendthrift,  and  it  became  Hobbes's  function  to 
assist  him  in  raising  frequent  loans.  Studies 
were  freely  neglected,  and  Hobbes  himself  '  almost 
forgot  his  Latin.'  Fortunately,  in  1610,  the  two 
youJig,  men  were  sent  to  make  the  grand  tour  of 
the  Continent,  and  travelled  together  over  a  great 
part  of  France,  Germany,  and  Italy.  As  yet 
Hobbes  appears  to  have  been  untouched  by  the 
new  scientific  movement,  though  it  was  only  in 
the  preceding  year  that  Kepler  had  published 

4 


LIFE 

the  first  two  of  his  famous  laws,  and  Galileo  was 
at  the  very  height  of  his  glory,  owing  to  his 
recent  discovery  of  the  satellites  of  Jupiter.  The 
main  effect  of  the  journey  was  to  revive  Hobbes's 
interest  in  his  neglected  literary  studies,  and  to 
send  him  home  with  a  fixed  determination  to 
make  himself  a  thorough  scholar.  The  resolve 
was  executed  so  successfully  that  Hobbes  not 
merely  became  one  of  the  most  vigorous  and 
luminous  of  English  writers,  but  learned  to 
handle  Latin,  still  the  general  language  of  the 
learned  world,  with  rare  force  and  fluency.  The 
first-fruits  of  this  renewed  interest  in  learning 
was  an  English  translation  of  Thucydides,  pub 
lished  in  1628-9,  for  the  purpose,  as  Hobbes  said 
at  the  time,  of  educating  his  readers  in  the  true 
principles  of  statesmanship.  Afterwards,  when 
his  absolutist  political  theories  had  been  fully 
developed,  he  wished  it  to  be  believed  that  his 
real  object  had  been  to  warn  Englishmen  against 
the  dangers  of  democracy,  by  showing  them  how 
much  wiser  a  single  great  statesman  is  than  a 
multitude. 

From  Hobbes's  admirer,  John  Aubrey,  we  learn 
something  about  the  circles  in  which  he  was 
moving  at  this  time  of  his  life.  Foremost  among 
his  friends  stands  Francis  Bacon,  who  '  loved  to 

5 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

converse  with  him,'  and  employed  him  on  the 
translation  of  some  of  the  famous  Essays,  notably 
that  on  The  True  Greatness  of  Kingdoms  and 
Estates,  into  Latin.  This  connection  can  be  shown 
to  belong  to  the  years  1621-6  when  Bacon,  after 
his  political  disgrace,  was  devoting  himself  en 
tirely  to  scientific  work  in  his  retreat  at  Gorham- 
bury.  The  influence  of  Bacon,  however,  has  left 
no  trace  on  Hobbes's  own  matured  thought.  He 
barely  mentions  the  Chancellor  in  his  writings, 
and  has  no  place  for  '  Baconian  induction '  in  his 
own  conception  of  scientific  method.  Bacon's 
zeal  for  experiment,  the  redeeming  feature  in  an 
otherwise  chaotic  scheme  of  thought,  is  entirely 
alien  to  the  essentially  deductive  and  systematic 
spirit  of  the  Hobbian  philosophy.  Other  friends 
of  this  period  were  Ben  Jonson,  the  reigning 
literary  dictator  of  London,  Edward  Herbert, 
Baron  Cherbury,  the  '  first  of  the  English  Deists/ 
the  antagonist  against  whom  Locke's  attack  on 
'  innate  ideas '  was  afterwards  to  be  directed,  and 
the  npw  forgotten  Scottish  poet,  Sir  Robert 
Ayton. 

In  1628  Hobbes's  ex-pupil  died,  after  a  two 
years'  tenure  of  the  Earldom  of  Devonshire, 
leaving  the  family  estates  heavily  encumbered. 
The  necessary  retrenchments  involved  a  tem- 

6 


LIFE 

porary  severance  of  Hobbes's  connection  with  the 
Cavendishes,  and  from  1629  to  1631  he  acted 
as  tutor  to  the  son  of  Sir  Gervase  Clifton,  a  gentle 
man  of  Nottinghamshire.  He  accompanied  this 
new  pupil  on  a  foreign  tour,  which  apparently 
extended  through  France  and  as  far  as  Venice. 
It  was  probably  during  this  period  that  an 
incident  occurred  which  was  to  exercise  a  lasting, 
and  not  entirely  happy  influence  on  the  whole  of 
Hobbes's  subsequent  thought.  At  the  age  of 
forty  he  was,  for  the  first  time,  introduced  to  the 
works  of  Euclid,  and  at  once  'fell  in  love  with 
geometry,'  being  attracted,  he  says,  more  by  the 
rigorous  manner  of  proof  employed  than  by  the 
matter  of  the  science.  (Mathematics,  we  must 
remember,  were  then  only  beginning  to  be  seriously 
studied  in  England.  Hobbes  tells  us  that  in  his 
undergraduate  days  geometry  was  still  looked 
upon  generally  as  a  form  of  the  '  Black  Art/  and 
it  was  not  until  1619  that  the  will  of  Sir  Henry 
Savile,  Warden  of  Merton  College,  established  the 
first  Professorships  of  Geometry  and  Astronomy 
at  Oxford.) 

In  1631  Hobbes  was  recalled  from  Paris  by 
the  widow  of  his  late  pupil  to  take  charge  of  the 
education  of  her  eldest  son,  the  third  Earl  of 
Devonshire,  then. a  boy  of  twelve.  By  1634  the 

7 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

lad  was  thought  old  enough  to  make  the  con 
tinental  tour,  and  Hobbes  accompanied  him  on 
a  journey  through  France  and  Italy,  from  which 
the  pair  did  not  return  until  1637.  This  third 
foreign  journey  was  destined  to  be  the  turning- 
point  of  Hobbes's  intellectual  life.  All  through 
the  journey  he  was  haunted  by  a  single  idea, 
the  thought  of  the  omnipresence  of  motion  in 
nature,  and  of  the  apparent  variety  of  natural 
objects  as  a  mere  effect  of  diversity  of  motion 
in  the  different  parts  of  body.  The  origin  of  this 
absorption  in  the  notion  of  motion  he  derives 
from  the  following  undated  incident.  In  a  com 
pany  of  learned  men,  among  whom  he  was  present, 
a  chance  reference  to  sensation  provoked  the  con 
temptuous  question,  '  And,  pray,  what  is  sense  ? ' 
Reflecting  long  on  this  chance  question,  Hobbes 
came  to  the  conclusion  that  if  all  bodies  were  at 
rest  or  all  moved  exactly  in  the  same  way,  there 
would  be  no  means  of  distinguishing  any  one 
thing  from  any  other,  and  therefore  no  sensation. 
Hence  not  only  must  the  whole  of  physical 
nature  consist,  as  Galileo  was  already  declaring, 
of  diversity  of  motions  of  homogeneous  particles, 
but  the  same  must  be  true  of  the  inner  world  of 
our  so-called  'mental  processes/  they  must  all  be 
but  so  many  diverse  motions  in  what  we  now 

8 


LIFE 

call  our  '  nervous  system.'  With  this  conclusion 
Hobbes's  path  as  a  philosopher  was  marked  out. 
His  task  was  to  bejhe  exhibition  of  all  the  facts 
of  the  universe,  and  more  particularly  those  of 
the  inner  life  of  emotion  and  will,  as  consequences 
of  the  primary  laws  _of_  motion.  Hence,  in  the 
preface  to  the  De  Corpore,  after  mentioning  as 
the  founders  of  true  physical  science  Copernicus, 
Kepler,  Galileo,  and  Harvey^  he  adds  that  the 
true  doctrine  of  civil  society  is  no  older  than  his 
own  book  De  Give. 

Evidence  discovered  by  Dr.  Ferdinand  Tonnies 
has  now  made  it  probable  that  the  facts  just 
described  belong  to  a  date  some  years  anterior  to 
the  journey  of  1637,  but,  in  any  case,  Hobbes's 
third  residence  abroad  marks  a  definite  epoch  in 
his  life.  It  is  the  date  at  which  he  first  takes  his 
place  as  a  recognised  member  of  the  band  of 
European  thinkers  who  were  aiming  at  the  syste-  ( 
matic  reconstruction  of  science.  In  Italy  he  met 
the  great  Galileo,  not  yet,  indeed,  blind,  but  con 
fined  by  the  Inquisition  to  his  villa,  and  a  little 
tarnished  in  his  renown  by  his  insincere  recanta 
tion.  Almost  more  important  were  the  connec 
tions  formed  on  the  return  to  Paris  in  1637. 
Here  Hobbes  became  one  of  the  circle  which 
centred  around  the  famous  Franciscan  friar, 

9 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

Marin  Mersenne,  who  performed  what,  in  the 
absence  of  scientific  journals,  was  the  indispens 
able  service  of  furthering  the  communication  of 
knowledge  by  bringing  learned  men  together,  in 
person  or  by  correspondence.  Mersenne's  cell, 
says  Hobbes,  was  more  to  him  than  all  the 
universities.  We  may  note  that  this  same  year 
saw  the  publication  of  the  first  work  of  another 
of  Mersenne's  constant  correspondents,  his  old 
school-fellow,  Rene  Descartes,  now  for  years  settled 
in  his  self-chosen  Dutch  seclusion. 

Before  the  end  of  1637  Hobbes  and  his  pupil 
were  once  more  in  England,  where  the  times,  as  we 
know,  now  began  to  be  singularly  troublous.  The 
next  two  years  saw  the  trial  of  Harnpden  for  his 
refusal  to  pay  ship-money,  the  Edinburgh  revolt 
against  the  ill-judged  attempt  to  force  Episcopacy 
on  Scotland,  the  signing  of  the  Solemn  League 
and  Covenant,  and  the  Scottish  invasion  of 
England.  In  virtue  of  his  connection  with  the 
Devonshire  family,  Hobbes  was  just  now  much  in 
the  society  of  the  more  moderate  Royalist  leaders, 
such  as  Falkland  and  Hyde,  and  the  result  was 
that  early  in  1640,  about  the  time  of  meeting  of 
the  Short  Parliament,  he  put  aside  his  wider 
philosophical  schemes  for  the  composition  of  a 
little  work  in  support  of  his  fundamental  political 

10 


LIFE 

conviction  that  the  an ti- social  tendencies  of 
human  nature  are  too  strong  and  deep-rooted  to 
be  held  in  check  by  anything  short  of  an  absolute 
authority,  free  from  all  control,  such  as  the 
English  Crown  might  be  jnade,  if  released  from 
all  dependence  on  Parliament.  The  work,  which 
bore  the  title,  The  Elements  of  Law,  and  contains 
one  of  the  clearest  and  fullest  of  Hobbes's  exposi 
tions  of  his  psychology,  was  not  printed,  but 
circulated  in  manuscript.  Ten  years  later  it  was 
published  in  an  imperfect  form  as  two  distinct 
essays,  Of  Human  Nature  and  De  Corpore 
Politico.  It  was^  not  until  1889  that  the  work 
was  printed  in  its  original  shape,  and  with  its 
original  title,  by  Dr.  Tonnies.  When  the  Long 
Parliament  met  towards  the  end  of  the  year, 
and  showed  its  temper  by  at  once  proceeding  to 
impeach  Strafford,  Hobbes's  native  timorousness 
got  the  better  of  him.  Fancying  that  the  author 
of  the  Elements  of  Law  might  be  the  next  victim, 
he  promptly  escaped  to  Paris,  not  to  return  for 
eleven  years.  In  after  days  he  oddly  represented 
this  excessive  alarm  as  giving  him  an  exceptional 
claim  on  royal  gratitude. 

His  flight  brought  him  back  to  Paris  in  the  very 
nick  of  time.  Mersenne  was  busy,  at  Descartes' 
request,  in  procuring  criticisms  from  learned  men 

ii 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

on  the  famous  Meditations,  then  just  about  to  be 
published.  One  such  set  of  criticisms  he  obtained 
from  Hobbes— those  which  now  figure  as  the 
'Third  Objections '—but  they  failed  to  achieve 
their  purpose.  Descartes  was  seeking  help  from 
the  criticisms  of  persons  in  sympathy  with  his 
general  line  of  thought.  What  he  got  from 
Hobbes  was  an  attack  on  his  fundamental  posi 
tions  by  a  thinker  of  radically  different  convic 
tions.  Hence  he  treated  the  'Objections'  very 
curtly,  even  refusing  to  admit  that  they  contained 
a  single  valid  inference,  nor  was  he  more  favour 
ably  impressed  by  Hobbes's  remarks  on  the 
Dioptrique  published  along  with  the  Discourse 
on  Method  (1637),  which  were  also  communicated 
to  him  by  Mersenne.  On  the  other  hand,  Hobbes 
contracted  an  enduring  friendship  with  another 
of  the  lights  of  Mersenne's  circle,  Pierre  Gassend, 
the  reviver  of  Epicureanism. 

During  1641  Hobbes  recast  in  Latin  his  exposi 
tion  of  his  psychological  and  political  doctrines , 
The  work  was  printed,  in  a  very  limited  edition 
in  1642  under  the  title  De  Give,  and  was  highly 
appreciated  even  by  Descartes.  It  was  reissued 
five  years  later  from  the  press  of  the  Elzevirs  at 
Amsterdam  as  Elementa  Philosophica  de  Give. 
Hobbes  had  meanwhile  been  (1646)  appointed 

12 


LIFE 

mathematical  tutor  to  the  Prince  of  Wales,  after 
wards  Charles  n.,  who  had  just  come  over  from 
Jersey.  The  engagement  cannot  have  lasted 
beyond  1648,  when  the  Prince  withdrew  to 
Holland,  and  was  possibly  ended  earlier  by  a 
dangerous  illness  which  overtook  Hobbes  in  1647. 
In  after  years  he  was  accustomed  to  meet  doubts 
as  to  his  religious  orthodoxy  by  an  appeal  to  his 
acquiescence,  during  this  illness,  in  the  minis 
trations  of  Dr.  Cosins  (afterwards  Bishop  of 
Durham). 

In  1651  came  out  an  English  version  of  the 
De  .Give:  Philosophical  Rudiments  concerning 
Government  and  Society.  During  the  same  year 
Hobbes  was  busy  with  the  composition  of  the 
work  by  which  he  is  now  best  known  to  the 
general  student,  Leviathan :  or  the  Matter,  Form, 
and  Power  of  a  Commonwealth  Ecclesiastical 
and  Civil,  which  appeared  in  London  at  the  end 
of  the  year.  The  book  consists  of  a  restatement 
of  the  general  philosophical  argument  for  abso 
lutism,  with  the  addition  of  a  long  and  bitter 
polemic  against  admitting  any  independent 
ecclesiastical  authority  other  than  the  civil 
sovereign.  A  specially  handsome  copy  of  the 
MS.  was  presented  to  Charles  n.,  now  King  of 
Scots,  on  his  return  to  Paris  after  the  adven- 

13 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

turous  escape  from  Worcester.  But  the  Anglican 
Royalists,  who  identified  the  cause  of  monarchy 
with  the  cause  of  the  English  Church,  were 
naturally  incensed  at  the  author's  consistent 
Erastianism  and  an ti- clericalism,  and  for  a  time 
contrived  to  keep  Hobbes  from  access  to  the  King. 
Between  this,  and  his  concern  as  to  the  way  in 
which  the  anti-papal  doctrines  of  Leviathan 
might  be  received  by  the  French  clergy,  Hobbes 
once  more  took  alarm,  and  made  his  way  back  to 
London  at  the  end  of  1651,  sending  in  his  formal 
submission  to  the  Council  of  State  shortly  after. 
There  was  just  now,  amid  the  general  confusion 
following  on  the  abolition  of  the  old  constitution, 
no  censorship  of  the  press  in  England  to  interfere 
with  his  publications.  Thus  it  carne  about  that 
the  Leviathan  could  be  published  in  London,  and 
that  so  much  of  the  great  systematic  work  on 
philosophy  as  was  ever  completed  appeared,  after 
all,  on  English  soil. 

Among  Hobbes's  personal  friends  of  this  period 

we  have  to  note  the  famous  Selden,  and  the  still 

more  famous   Harvey.     With   Milton,   the  chief 

man  of  letters  among  the  anti-Royalists,  he  had 

no  relations,  though  it  is  recorded  that  Milton 

i  '  did  not  like  him,  but  would  acknowledge  him  to 

\  be  a  man  of  great  parts.'     Hobbes,  for  his  part, 


LIFE 

declared,  comparing  Milton's  famous  Defence  of 
the  People  of  England  with  Salmasius'  Defence  of 
the  King,  'they  are  very  good  Latin  both,  and 
hardly  to  be  judged,  which  is  better,  and  both  very 
ill  reasoning,  hardly  to  be  judged,  which  is  worse.'  - 

Hobbes  was  now  at  last,  at  the  age  of  64,  work 
ing  on  the  reasoned  exposition  of  his  system. 
When  completed,  the  scheme  was  to  contain 
three  divisions :  (1)  of  Body,  the  presentation  of 
the  fundamental  principles  of  the  new  science  of 
motion,  and  the  deduction  from  them  of  a  doctrine 
of  physics ;  (2)  of  Man,  a  further  deduction  from 
the  same  principles,  of  human  physiology  and 
psychology ;  (3)  of  the  Body  Politic,  a  deduction 
of  ethics,  politics,  and  sociology  from  the  results 
reached  in  the  previous  sections.  Thus  the  final 
achievement  would  have  been  the  deduction  of 
social  science  as  a  body  of  corollaries  from  the 
principles  of  mechanics.  From  the  first,  the 
execution  of  this  plan  was  delayed  by  contro 
versies,  largely  provoked  by  Hobbes's  own  mis 
takes,  and  the  great  scheme  never  reached  fulfil 
ment.  The  first  section  was,  indeed,  completed, 
but  the  second  remained  a  mere  fragment,  and 
the  third  is  represented  only  by  works  like  the 
De  Give  and  Leviathan,  originally  composed  as 
independent  treatises. 

15 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

The  De  Corpore,  though  in  the  press  in  1654, 
did  not  appear  until  1655,  the  reason  of  the  delay 
being  that,  during  the  interval,  Hobbes  had  dis 
covered  flaws  in  the  quadrature  of  the  circle 
which  he  fancied  himself  to  have  found,  and  of 
which  he  had  been  rather  rashly  boasting  in 
advance.  By  the  time  of  publication  he  had 
further  become  implicated  in  the  eternal  dispute 
about  the  freedom  of  the  will,  and  the  con 
sequence  of  his  double  controversy  with  the 
mathematicians  and  the  theologians  was  that, 
when  the  De  Homine  at  last  appeared  in  1658,  it 
turned  out  to  contain  nothing  but  a  few  chapters 
on  optics,  along  with  a  brief  sketch  of  elementary 
psychology.  For  many  years  after  1655  Hobbes's 
career  as  an  author  is  mainly  the  history  of  a 
series  of  acrimonious  disputes  with  mathematical 
and  theological  opponents. 

The  theological  disputes  go  back  ultimately  to 
the  year  1646,  when  Hobbes  had  held  a  verbal 
discussion  with  Bramhall,  Bishop  of  Londonderry, 
and  afterwards  Archbishop  of  Armagh,  in  which 
he  maintained  the  determinist  view  of  human 
action  against  the  Arminian  and  High  Anglican 
doctrine  of  free  will.  Both  parties  had  after 
wards  reduced  the  substance  of  their  contentions 
to  writing,  though  with  an  understanding  that 
16 


LIFE 

nothing  should  be  published  on  either  side.  In 
1654,  however,  an  unknown  person  who  had  pro 
cured  a  copy  of  Hobbes's  MS.,  which  contains 
one  of  the  clearest  statements  ever  made  of  the 
argument  for  determinism,  published  it  under 
the  title  A  Discourse  concerning  Liberty  and^ 
Necessity.  Bramhall,  angered  at  what  he  sup 
posed  to  be  the  bad  faith  of  Hobbes,  replied  in 
1655  by  publishing  his  own  original  contribution 
to  the  controversy,  Hobbes  rejoining  in  the  next 
year  with  a  fresh  set  of  Questions  concerning 
Liberty,  Necessity,  and  C/tance.  The  '  questions ' 
were,,  in  turn,  attacked  by  Bramhall  in  1658  in  a 
work  to  which  was  appended  a  violent  attack  on 
Leviathan,  facetiously  styled  The  Catching  of 
Leviathan,  the  Great  Whale.  Hobbes  took  no 
notice  of  this  onslaught  beyond  drawing  up,  ten 
years  later  (1668),  a  refutation  of  Bramhall's  im 
putations  of  impiety,  which,  like  most  of  his 
writings  of  that  time,  was  not  published  until 
after  his  death. 

More  damaging  for  Hobbes  was  his  violent 
quarrel  with  the  Oxford  mathematicians,  itself  an 
outgrowth  of  his  attacks  on  the  Universities. 
Like  many  other  persons  who  have  never  quite 
made  themselves  at  home  in  geometry,  Hobbes 
unluckily  conceived  the  notion  that  he  had  solved 
B  17 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

the  famous  (and  insoluble)  problems  of  the  quad 
rature  of  the  circle  and  the  subdivision  of  the 
angle  into  any  given  number  of  equal  parts.  In 
palliation  of  his  delusion  it  may  be  pleaded  that 
neither  problem  was  definitely  known  in  his  day 
to  be  insoluble  by  the  methods  of  elementary 
geometry.  In  fact  the  insolubility  of  the  more 
famous  of  the  two,  that  of  the  quadrature,  has 
only  been  finally  demonstrated  in  our  own  time 
by  Lindemann,  though  a  sounder  mathematical 
instinct  would,  no"  ^doubt,  have  suggested  to 
Hobbes  that  it  probably  was  not  to  be  solved. 
His  fault  lay  not  so  much  in  attempting  to 
grapple  with  the  problem  as  in  the  obstinacy 
with  which  he  refused  to  recognise  the  futility  of 
his  results,  even  when  they  had  been  repeatedly 
exposed  by  the  first  mathematicians  of  the  day. 
A  few  words  must  be  said  as  to  the  history  of  the 
quarrel.  Hobbes  had,  in  Leviathan,  made  a  bitter 
attack  on  the  Universities,  which  he  regarded  as 
v  the  chief  supporters  of  clerical  pretensions,  and 
had  particularly  enlarged  on  their  ignorance  of 
mathematics  and  natural  science.  He  did  not 
know,  or  forgot,  that  the  Oxford  of  1651  was  a 
very  different  place  from  the  Oxford  of  half  a 
century  earlier.  The  Savilian  Professorships  had 
done  much  to  raise  the  standard  of  mathematical 

,8 


LIFE 

and  physical  knowledge,  and  Oxford  was  already 
the  home  of  an  eager  band  of  scientific  workers 
who  were  subsequently  to  form  the  nucleus  of  the 
Royal  Society.     The  resentment  of  the  Oxford 
men  of  science  against  Hobbes's  undeserved  stric 
tures  had  already  found  expression  in  the  Vin- 
dicice  Academiarum  (1654)  of  Seth  Ward,  Savilian 
Professor  of  Astronomy,  a  rejoinder  to  an  attack 
on  the  Universities  by  the  Rev.  John  Webster, 
also  honourably  known  as  one  of  the  first  writers 
against  the  belief  in  witchcraft.     Ward,  however, 
took  only  a  minor  part  in  the  long  and  angry 
controversy  which  followed  on  the  publication  of 
the  De  Gorpore,  Hobbes's  principal  assailant  being 
Ward's  associate,  John  Wallis,  Savilian  Professor 
of  Geometry,  the  most  eminent  English  mathe 
matician  of  the  generation  before  Newton.    Three 
months  after  the  issue  of  the  De  Corpore  in  1655 
followed  Wallis's  Elenchus  Geometrice  Hobbiance, 
exposing  the  fallacies  of  Hobbes's  quadrature,  and 
proving,  with  the  aid  of  an  unbound  copy  of  the 
work,  that  his  '  solutions,'  such  as  they  were,  had 
been  repeatedly  modified  owing  to  their  author's 
discovery  of  errors  in  them  after  they  had  been 
sent  to  the  press.     In  1656  there  came  out  an 
English   version   of    the   De   Corpore,  made    by 
Hobbes's  instruction,  but  not  from  his  own  hand 
19 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

(Concerning  Body,  1656).  Here  the  'solutions' 
were  given  as  mere  'aggressions/  or  approxima 
tions,  but,  as  a  set-off,  the  book  contained  an 
appendix,  Six  Lessons  to  the  Oxford  Professors, 
decrying  the  whole  of  Wallis's  mathematical 
work.  Wallis  rejoined  in  three  months  with  a 
Due  Correction  for  Mr.  Hobbes,  which,  in  its  turn, 
provoked  in  1657  an  abusive  reply  from  Hobbes, 
and  the  inevitable  counter-reply  from  Wallis.  In 
1660  Hobbes  returned  to  the  fray  with  five  Latin 
dialogues,  Examinatio  et  Emendatio  Mathema 
tical  Hodiernce.  Next  year  he  proceeded  to  bring 
out  a  professed  solution  of  the  third  of  the 
famous  ancient  problems,  the  duplication  of  the 
cube,  which  was,  as  usual,  duly  refuted  by  Wallis. 
In  1662  Hobbes  went  on  to  aim  a  blow  at  the 
recently  incorporated  Eoyal  Society,  in  which 
Wallis  was  a  prominent  figure,  by  attacking 
Boyle's  experiments  with  the  air-pump,  and  en 
deavouring  to  show  that  mere  experimentation 
adds  nothing  to  our  insight  into  nature.  Boyle 
replied  with  an  Examen  of  Mr.  Hobbes  his  Dia- 
logus,  and  Wallis,  with  a  scathing  satire  on 
Hobbes's  mathematics,  Hobbius  Heauton  Timo- 
rumenus.  Hobbes  wisely  left  this  exposure  un 
answered,  but  avenged  himself  signally  upon 
Wallis's  incidental  political  insinuation  against 
20 


LIFE 

him  of  having  favoured  Cromwell's  usurpation, 
by  a  letter  On  the  Reputation,  Loyalty,  Manners, 
and  Religion  of  T.  H.,  in  which  Wallis  was  re 
minded  of  the  service  he  had  done  to  the  Parlia 
mentarians  by  deciphering  the  papers  of  Charles  i. 
captured  at  Naseby.  For  some  years  after  this 
the  controversy  slumbered,  but  was  revived  again 
by  Hobbes  in  1666.  Wallis  continued  to  refute 
Hobbes's  various  mathematical  papers  as  they 
came  out  until  1672,  and  then  allowed  the  dis 
pute  to  drop.  Hobbes,  for  his  part,  still  kept  up 
the  game,  and  even  in  his  latest  work  Decameron 
Physiologicum,  produced  when  he  was  over 
ninety,  contrived  to  insert  a  new  '  demonstration ' 
of  the  equality  of  a  straight  line  to  an  arc  of  a 
circle. 

Meanwhile,  the  Restoration  had  made  some 
change  in  the  philosopher's  position.  He  was 
met  and  warmly  welcomed  by  Charles  n.  a  few 
days  after  his  return  to  England,  encouraged  to 
present  himself  at  Court,  had  his  portrait  painted 
at  the  king's  expense,  and  received  a  pension  of 
£100,  which,  unfortunately,  was  not  always  regu 
larly  paid.  Court  favour,  however,  could  only, 
partly  protect  the  author  of  Leviathan  from  the 
animosity  of  the  clergy  whom  he  had  handled  so 
roughly.  In  connection  with  the  Bill  brought 
21 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

into  the  Commons  in  1666,  under  the  influence  of 
the  emotions  aroused  by  the  Plague  and  the  Great 
Fire,  for  the  suppression  of  atheism  and  profanity, 
a  Committee  was  appointed  to  receive  informa 
tions  against  atheistical,  blasphemous,  and  pro 
fane  books,  among  which  Leviathan  was  specified 
by  name.  The  Bill  fell  through  in  the  Lords,  but 
Hobbes,  who  began  to  fear  that  he  was  in  personal 
danger,  made,  it  is  said,  a  show  of  conformity,  and 
took  care,  in  reprinting  Leviathan  in  Latin,  to 
add  an  appendix  intended  to  show  that  his  doc 
trines  did  not  formally  contradict  the  Nicene 
Creed.  He  even  took  the  trouble  to  draw  up  a 
dissertation  on  the  state  of  the  English  law  of 
Heresy,  to  prove  that  he  could  not  legally  be 
burned.  From  this  time  on,  Hobbes  only  retained 
Court  protection  on  condition  of  abstention  from 
all  publications  on  political  and  religious  topics. 
For  the  Latin  edition  of  his  Opera  Omnia,  which 
appeared  in  1668,  he  had  to  find  a  publisher  in 
Holland,  and  Pepys  records  in  his  diary  for  Sep 
tember  3rd  of  the  same  year  that  a  second-hand 
copy  of  Leviathan  (which  had  originally  come 
out  at  8s.)  cost  him  24s.,  and  that  the  price  was 
still  rising,  as  the  book  could  not  be  reprinted. 
|  Similarly  a  new  treatise  of  the  same  date,  Behe- 
\  moth,  the  History  of  the  Civil  Wars,  was  pro- 

22 


LIFE 

scribed  by  the  censor.  In  spite  of  age  and  rebuffs, 
Hobbes  still  continued  to  write  on  a  variety  of 
topics,  ranging  from  mathematics  to  English  Law 
and  Church  History,  and  was  frequently  visited, 
on  account  of  his  fame  as  a  scholar  and  philo 
sopher,  by  foreign  admirers  of  learning  who  found 
themselves  in  England. 

In  1669  his  clerical  enemies  found  a  charac 
teristic  method  of  annoying  him.  Daniel  Scar- 
gill,  a  disreputable  Fellow  of  Corpus  Christi 
College,  Cambridge,  was  deprived  of  his  degree 
and  expelled  from  the  University  for  having 
publicly  maintained  theses  taken  from  Leviathan. 
Scargill  was  persuaded  to  make  an  edifying  re 
cantation,  in  which  the  blame  for  his  loose  life 
was  laid  on  the  supposed  immoral  principles  he 
had  imbibed  from  the  books  of  Hobbes,  who, 
thanks  to  the  censorship,  was  unable  to  protest 
against  the  imputations.  Five  years  later,  Oxford 
followed  suit.  Dr.  Fell,  Dean  of  Christchurch, 
and  hero  of  a  well-known  uncomplimentary 
epigram,  took  advantage  of  his  connection  with 
the  University  Press  to  strike  out  of  the  Latin 
version  of  Anthony  Wood's  History  and  Anti 
quities  of  Oxford  all  the  appreciative  epithets 
which  the  English  original  had  bestowed  on 
Hobbes,  and  to  replace  them  by  terms  of  abuse. 
23 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

Hobbes  was  this  time  permitted  by  the  king  to 
publish  a  letter  of  remonstrance,  but  the  only  effect 
was  to  draw  from  Dr.  Fell  an  outrageous  additional 
note  to  the  book  in  which  Hobbes  was  reviled 
more  coarsely  than  before.      Meanwhile  the  old 
man  had  for  a  while  amused  himself  by  a  return 
to  the  literary  pursuits  of  his  earlier  days.     In 
1672  he  composed  a  succinct  account  of  his  life, 
works,  and  various  controversies  in  Latin  elegiacs, 
and  in  1673  and  the   year  or   two   following   a 
complete   version  of  the   Iliad  and  Odyssey  in 
English   rhyme,  a   sufficiently  arduous   task   for 
an    old    man    well    on    towards    his    ninetieth 
year.     In  1675   he  finally  left  London,  residing 
for  the  few  years  of  life  still  left  to  him  alternately 
at  the  two  Derbyshire  seats  of  the  Devonshire 
family,    Chatsworth    and    Hardwick.     His    last 
work,   Decameron    Physiologicum,    was,    as    we 
have    already    seen,   produced  in    1678    at    the 
age    of   ninety.     At   the    end    of    the   following 
year,   when    the    family    moved,  as   usual,   from 
Ghatsworth  to  Hardwick  for  the  winter,  Hobbes 
refused   to   be   left   behind.       But    the    journey 
proved  too  much   for   his   strength,   and   a   few 
days  after  reaching  Hardwick  the  old  philosopher 
was   struck   by  paralysis,  of  which   he   died   on 
J^^m^be^rW^^t  the  age  of  ninety-one  years 
and  eight  months.     The  body  was  laid  to  rest  in 
24 


LIFE 

a  modest  grave  in  the  parish  church  of  Hault 
Hucknall,  just  outside  the  park  gates. 

Hobbes's  personal  appearance  is  well  known  to 
us  from  various  portraits,  and  from  the  descrip 
tion  of  his  friend  Aubrey.  He  was  tall,  erect, 
and  strikingly  handsome  of  face.  Though  sickly 
in  youth,  in  manhood  and  later  age  he  was  excep 
tionally  healthy  and  vigorous,  being  able  even 
at  seventy-five  to  enjoy  an  occasional  game  of 
tennis.  His  personal  habits  were  regular,  and 
in  later  age,  abstemious,  though,  according  to 
Aubrey,  he  owned  to  having  been  drunk  about  a 
hundred  'times  in  his  life,  a  moderate  allowance 
in  those  days  especially  as  the  good  gentleman 
seems  to  have  regarded  occasional  drunkenness 
as  medicinal.  There  is  a  report  of  the  existence 
of  a  natural  daughter,  for  whom  he  is  said  to 
have  provided.  With  respect  to  his  character, 
there  is  little  to  be  objected  against  except  his 
natural  timidity,  and  a  certain  lack  of  emotional 
warmth,  which  did  not,  however,  prevent  him 
from  proving  a  benefactor  to  his  relatives  and  a 
steady  and  constant  friend.  In  spite  of  his  rather 
cynical  theories  of  human  nature,  he  appears  to  } 
have  been  reasonably  charitable  to  real  distress, 
and  it  is  highly  creditable  to  him,  as  well  as  to 
his  protectors,  the  family  of  Cavendish,  that, 
having  once  resolved  on  the  life  of  a  scholar  and 
25 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

thinker,  he  avoided  all  temptations  to  desert  his 
modest  position  for  the  sake  of  worldly  advan 
tage,  and  that  so  much  care  was  taken  to  make 
that  position  compatible  with  his  unchecked 
pursuit  of  his  chosen  studies.  If  we  look 
in  vain  in  his  life  and  writings  for  any  traces 
of  deep  spirituality  and  ethical  inwardness, 
the  same  thing  may  be  said  of  Descartes,  and, 
in  fact,  of  most  of  the  eminent  thinkers  of  an 

'  exceedingly  worldly  and  unspiritual  age.  It  is 
not  often  that  we  find,  as  we  do  in  Plato,  the 
combination  in  one  person  of  intense  spiritual 
earnestness  with  the  faculty  of  cool  and  keen 
rationalistic  analysis.  Apart  from  its  splendid 
trust  in  the  competence  of  the  human  intellect 
to  discover  the  truth  of  things,  there  is  not  much 

\  in  Hobbes's  philosophical  scheme  to  arouse  the 
enthusiasm  of  the  young  and  ardent,  and  more 
than  a  little  which  is  positively  repellent.  But 
there  are  few  writers  whose  work  is  more  fruit 
ful  of  suggestions  for  the  matured  and  reflective 
intellect  which  has  grown  suspicious  of  all  en 
thusiasm,  even  of  its  own,  and  demands  before 
all  things  calm  and  impartial  reasoned  analysis. 
Perhaps  the  best  proof  of  Hobbes's  real  genius 
is  that  even  his  worst  errors  are  so  much  more 
instructive  than  the  truths  of  lesser  men. 

26 


CHAPTER   II 

PHILOSOPHY,   ITS   SCOPE   AND   METHODS 

HOBBES'S  main  influence  on  the  thought  both  of  his 
own  and  of  subsequent  times  has  been  felt  almost 
exclusively  in  the  domain  of  Ethics  and  Politics. 
He  is  primarily  important  to  us  as  the  herald  of 
a  new  epoch  in  English  thinking,  an  epoch  which, 
we  might  fairly  say,  was  closed  only  the  other 
day  by  the  death  of  Herbert  Spencer.  When  we 
think  of  him,  it  is  usually  as  the  first  in  the  long 
succession  of  English  empirical  psychologists,  the 
earliest  English  writer  of  many  who  have  sought 
to  found  a  purely  naturalistic  system  of  moral 
and  political  science  on  the  basis  of  biological 
and  psychological  fact.  But  it  is  equally  true 
that  Hobbes  ends  an  epoch.  He  is  the  last 
English  philosophical  writer,  with  the  single  ex 
ception  of  Spencer,  to  understand  the  word 
1  philosophy '  in  the  wide  sense  put  upon  it  in  the 
Middle  Ages,  as  the  systematised  and  codified 
body  of  all  rational  human  knowledge.  With  his 

27 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

immediate  successor,  Locke,  begins  that  distinc 
tion  between  science  and  philosophy  by  which 
the  scope  of  the  latter  is  closely  restricted  to 
episteinological  inquiries  into  the  conditions  and 
nature  of  knowledge  in  general,  and  psychological 
investigations  into  its  growth,  while  the  task  of 
extending  the  contents  of  our  knowledge  of  the 
extra-subjective  world  is  made  over  exclusively 
to  the  sciences — a  distinction  which  has  ever 
since,  for  good  and  bad,  dominated  English  philo 
sophy.  From  Hobbes's  own  point  of  view,  then, 
his  doctrine  of  Man  and  Society  cannot  be  fully 
appreciated  unless  we  consider  it,  in  connection 
with  the  rest  of  his  system,  as  an  integral  part  of 
that  body  of  deductions  from  the  general  laws 
of  motion  which  constitutes  science.  For  this 
reason,  as  well  as  for  the  intrinsic  value  of  many 
of  his  thoughts  on  the  nature  and  methods  of 
science,  it  is  essential  to  examine  Hobbes's  general 
theory  of  the  range  and  the  procedure  of  science 
before  considering  his  achievements  as  a  theorist 
in  the  fields  of  morals  and  sociology. 

The  definition  of  philosophy,  as  given  at  the 
beginning  of  the  De  Corpore — our  citations  are 
from  the  English  version  of  1656— runs  thus: 
'Philosophy  is  such  knowledge  of  effects  or 
appearances  as  we  acquire  by  true  ratiocination 
28 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

from  the  knowledge  we  have  first  of  their  causes 
or  generations,  and,  again,  of  such  causes  or  genera 
tions  as  may  be  from  knowing  first  their  effects.' 
Here  the  words  '  by  true  ratiocination '  are  in 
tended  to  exclude  from  philosophy  knowledge 
directly  given  in  sense  perception  or  resting 
merely  upon  unsystematised  experience,  while  the 
expression  'such  causes  ...  as  may  be/  in  the 
second  clause  of  the  sentence,  alludes  to  Hobbes's 
view  that  by  reasoning  backward  from  '  effects ' 
to  their  '  causes/  we  can  never  discover  the  '  cause ' 
of  a  given  '  effect/  but  on.ly  one  or  more  alterna 
tive  '  causes '  by  any  one  of  which  the  result 
might  have  been  '  produced/ 

Philosophy  then  is,  in  short,  reasoned  know 
ledge,  and,  if  we  ask  why  we  ought  to  set  a  value 
on  such  knowledge,  Hobbes  replies,  even  more 
emphatically  than  Bacon,  'for  the  sake  of  its 
practical  consequences.'  'The  end  of  knowledge 
is  power,  and  the  use  of  theorems  ...  is  for  the 
construction  of  problems  ;  and  lastly,  the  scope  of 
all  speculation  is  the  performing  of  some  action,  or 
thing  to  be  done '  (Concerning  Body,  i.  6).  In  par 
ticular,  the  utility  of  '  moral  and  civil  philosophy  ' 
is  to  be  measured  by  the  calamities  which  arise 
from  ignorance  of  it.  All  the  avoidable 
calamities  of  human  life,  says  Hobbes,  with 
29 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

characteristic  exaggeration,  are  due  to  war.  And 
men  go  to  war,  not  because  they  wish  to  do  so, 
or  because  they  do  not  know  that  war  is  pro- 
^ductive  of  evil  effects,  but  because  they  do  not 
w  the  true  causes  of  war  and  peace.  That 
is,  they  are  uninstructed  in  the  true  principles  of 
civil  and  political  obedience,  which  had,  in  fact, 
according  to  Hobbes,  been  formulated  for  the 
first  time  in  1642  in  his  own  De  Give.  A  true 
system  of  Philosophy,  in  which  the  principles  of 
morals  and  politics  should  be  rigorously  deduced 
from  the  fundamental  axioms  of  science,  would 
therefore  act  as  a  universal  peacemaker. 

Philosophy,  then,  is  sharply  distinguished  by 
its  reasoned  form  from  history,  the  mere  record 
of  past  experience ;  '  whereas  sense  and  memory 
are  but  knowledge  of  fact,  which  is  a  thing  past 
and   irrecoverable,  science  is   the   knowledge   of 
consequences  and  dependence  of  one  fact  upon 
another'  (Leviathan,  c.  v.).     The   peculiarity  of 
philosophy  or  science  is  that  its  results  are  at 
once  universal  and  exact.     'Experience  conclu-j 
deth  nothing  universally,'  but  'nothing  is  produced [ 
by  reasoning  aright  but  general,  eternal,  and  im- .! 
mutable  truths.'     It  is  a  notable  peculiarity  of 
Hobbes's  doctrine  that,  while  he  agrees  with  the 
ordinary  empiricist  that  'the  first  beginnings  of 
30 

\ 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

knowledge  are  the  phantasms  of  sense  and 
imagination/  he  almost  entirely  neglects  the 
problem  of  inductive  logic,  how  '  general  eternal 
and  immutable  truths '  can  be  educed  from  these 
particular  isolated  '  phantasms/ 

From  the  definition  above  given,  it  follows  at 
once  that,  since  philosophy  treats  only  of  '  genera 
tions  '  or  causal  processes,  there  can  be  no  philo 
sophical  knowledge  of  any  being  which  has  no 
cause,  and  consequently  no  philosophy  of  any 
thing  eternal.  Hence,  there  is  no  science  of  God, 
since  God  is,  by  definition,  an  uncaused  and 
eternal  being.  Theology  is  thus,  at  a  stroke,  ex 
cluded  from  the  range  of  scientific  knowledge. 
Similarly,  since  all  causation  is  production  of  one 
motion  by  another,  there  is  no  science  of  any 
thing  except  bodies ;  the  profession  of  philosophy 
is  'to  search  out  the  properties  of  bodies  from 
their  generation,  or  their  generation  from  their 
properties.'  Hobbes  will  not  even  allow  that  we 
can  form  any  intelligible  concept  of  anything 
incorporeal,  and  contends  that  when  God  is  said 
by  the  official  Anglican  theology  to  be  '  without 
body,'  this  is  a  mere  vague  expression  of  reverence. 
In  strictness,  according  to  him,  there  is  no  definite 
concept  attached  to  the  name  '  God,'  and  it  is  on 
this  ground  that  he  criticises  Descartes'  argu- 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

ment  from  my  possession  of  an  '  idea  of  God '  to 
the  actual  existence  of  God.  Hobbes  replies 
(Third  Objections  to  the  Meditations),  that  the  in 
ference  is  worthless,  since  I  have  no  '  idea '  of  God 
at  all.  ^All  knowledge  of  God  requires  revelation, 
and  revelation  needs  to  be  accredited  by  miracles. 
Since  miracles  have  ceased,  a  point  on  which 
Hobbes  agrees  with  orthodox  Protestants,  no  one 
can  now  claim  to  be  heard  when  he  alleges  a 
divine  revelation  as  a  reason  for  disobedience  to 
his  civil  sovereign.  It  is  our  duty  to  accept  the 
theology  promulgated  by  the  State,  not  because  it 
is  true,  but  because  it  is  official.  '  Religion  is  not 
philosophy  but  law.' 

Hobbes's  general  position  as  to  the  limits  of 
science  is  thus  closely  akin  to  that  which  we 
should  nowadays  call  positivistic.  Science  ex 
tends  only  so  far  as  the  world  of  bodies  moving 
in  accord  with  fixed  mechanical  law,  and  no 
further.  What  distinguishes  Hobbes  from  most 
modern  representatives  of  this  view  is  that  he 
does  not  combine  it,  as  they  do,  with  the  further 
assertion  that  the  whole  of  the  knowledge  thus 
acquired  is  merely  '  relative,'  or  concerned  solely 
with  '  phenomena,'  which  are  manifestations  of  an 
underlying  unknown,  and  perhaps  unknowable, 
reality.  That  bodies  really  and  objectively  exist, 
32 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

and  that  the  laws  of  their  motion  can  be  dis 
covered,  he  simply  assumes  as  an  unquestionable 
fact ;  he  has  no  inkling  of  the  deeper  problem  of 
Descartes'  Meditations,  how  it  is  possible  for  the 
individual  mind  to  be  assured  of  anything  outside 
the  circle  of  its  own  states. 

From  the  definition  of  philosophy  as  the  know 
ledge  of  bodies,  the  threefold  division  of  the 
subject  at  once  follows.  For  bodies  are  either 
natural  or  artificial.  Natural  bodies,  again,  in 
clude,  among  others,  one  class  which  is  of  supreme 
importance,  inasmuch  as  it  is  the  object  of  all 
our  psychological  study  of  sensation,  thought,  and 
emotion,  the  bodies  of  human  beings.  An  arti 
ficial  body  is  what  we  commonly  call  a  society  or 
commonwealth.  The  society  or  commonwealth  is 
just  as  much  a  single  body,  and  governed  just  as 
completely  by  the  general  laws  of  the  motion  of 
bodies,  as  the  individual  organism.  Its  only  dis 
tinctive  characteristic  is  that  it  is  artificial ;  i.e.  it 
owes  its  origin  to  the  voluntary  agreement  of  the 
persons  who  form  its  constituent  members.  Hence 
philosophy,  as  a  whole,  falls  into  three  parts, 
the  doctrine  of  body  in  general,  the  doctrine  of 
the  human  body  in  particular,  the  doctrine  of 
the  artificial  body,  or  commonwealth.  '  Two  chief 
kinds  of  bodies,  and  very  different  from  one 
c  33 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

another,  offer  themselves  to  such  as  search  after 
their  generation  and  properties ;  one  whereof, 
being  the  work  of  nature,  is  called  a  natural  body  : 
the  other  is  called  a  commonwealth,  and  is 
made  by  the  wills  and  agreement  of  men.  And 
from  these  spring  the  two  parts  of  philosophy 
called  Natural  and  Civil  ...  In  the  first  place, 
therefore  (after  I  have  set  down  such  premisses  as 
appertain  to  the  nature  of  philosophy  in  general), 
I  will  discourse  of  bodies  natural,  in  the  second 
of  the  dispositions  and  manners  of  men,  and  in 
the  third  of  the  civil  duties  of  subjects.' — (Con 
cerning  Body,  i.  9.) 

By  the  premisses  which  appertain  to  the  nature 
of  philosophy  in  general  are  meant,  of  course,  the 
general  principles  of  logic  and  method,  and  it  is 
from  the  account  of  them  that  we  have  to  collect 
Hobbes's  views  on  the  theory  of  knowledge. 
Scientific  method,  then,  has  two  branches,  reason 
ing  from  general  principles  (definitions  and 
axioms),  to  their  consequences,  or,  as  Hobbes 
phrases  it,  from  causes  to  their  effects,  and  this  is 
synthesis;  reasoning  from  the  facts  to  the  prin 
ciples  involved,  from  effects  to  causes,  and  this  is 
analysis.  Synthesis  and  analysis  thus  correspond 
to  our  popular  distinction  between  the  deductive 
and  inductive  uses  of  logic.  Only  the  former,  the 
34 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

purely  deductive  type  of  reasoning,  is  rigidly  cer 
tain  and  yields  perfectly  determinate  conclusions.  A 
The  latter  is  essentially  hypothetical,  and  consists 
merely  in  pointing  out  such  principles  as  would 
lead  deductively  to  the  observed  results.  Hence 
Hobbes,  like  Epicurus,  explicitly  maintains  that 
different  theories  as  to  the  '  cause '  of  an  observed 
fact  may  be  equally  true,  if  each  would  equally 
lead  to  consequences  which  agree  with  observed 
facts.  In  modern  language,  his  theory  of  method 
makes  '  induction '  to  consist  simply  in  the  forma 
tion  of  explanatory  hypotheses,  apart  from  the 
further  task  of  complete  verification  by  showing 
that  any  explanation  other  than  that  adopted 
would  lead  to  results  which  conflict  with  fact. 
Like  Jevons,  he  regards  '  induction '  as  being 
merely  the  inverse  operation  corresponding  to 
the  direct  operation  of  deduction,  as  division 
or  integration  corresponds  to  multiplication  or 
differentiation.  Hence  he  held  that  the  Royal 
Society  was  proceeding  on  altogether  false  lines  in 
attempting  to  advance  physical  science  by  direct 
experiment  rather  than  by  reasoning  deductively 
from  preassumed  general  theories.  Hence,  too, 
his  uniform  silence  as  to  the  '  inductive '  method 
of  Bacon,  the  avowed  object  of  which  was  to 
eliminate  the  'anticipation  of  nature'  by  the 
35 


THOMAS  HO 

framing  of  initial  hypotheses  altogether  from  the 
work  of  science. 

Now  the  ultimate  first  principles  of  deductive 

science  are  all,  according  to  Hobbes,  definitions, 

that  'is,  statements   of  the   meaning   of  names. 

Everything  in  science,  therefore,  turns  upon  the 

original  definitions ;  science  is  merely  the  correct 

deduction   of  the   consequences  implied   in  the 

giving  of  names.     And  names,  Hobbes  holds,  were 

originally  given  arbitrarily.     '  For  it  is  true  that, 

e.g.  man  is  a  living  creature,  but  it  is  for  this 

reason,  that  it  pleased  men  to  impose  both  those 

names  on  the  same  thing '  (Concerning  Body,  iii.  8). 

This  point  comes   out  clearly  in  the  famous 

definition   of  a   name   (Ib.,  ii.   4):   'A   name  is 

a  word  taken  at  pleasure  to  serve  for  a  mark 

which  may  raise  in  our  minds  a  thought  like  to 

some  thought  we  had  before,  and  which,  being 

pronounced  to  others,  may  be  to  them  a  sign  of 

what  thought  the  speaker  had,  or  had  not,  before 

in  his  mind.'    Consistently  with  this  view,  Hobbes 

adopts  an  ultra-nominalist  position  in  logic.     The 

only  names   which   directly  denote  realities  are 

singular    names   of    individual    bodies;    general 

terms,  or  common  names,  do  not  directly  denote 

an  object  at  all.     There  is,  e.g.  no  such  object  as 

'  man  in  general.'     '  This  word  universal  is  never 

36 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

the  name  of  anything  existent  in  nature,  nor  of 
any  idea  or  phantasm  formed  in  the  mind,  but 
always  the  name  of  some  word  or  name,  so  that 
when  a  living  creature,  a  stone,  a  spirit,  or  any 
other  thing  is  said  to  be  universal,  it  is  not  to  be 
understood  that  any  man,  stone,  etc.,  ever  was  or 
can  be  universal,  but  only  that  these  words  are 
universal  names,  that  is,  names  common  to  many 
things'  (76.,  ii.  9).  A  proposition  is  'a  speech 
consisting  of  two  names  copulated,  by  which  he 
that  speaketh,  signifies  he  conceives  the  later 
name  to  be  the  name  of  the  same  thing  whereof 
the  former  is  the  name '  (/&.,  iii.  2). 

Thus  Hobbes's  doctrine  as  to  the  import  of 
propositions  is  that  their  whole  meaning  is  that 
the  predicate  is  a  name  of  the  same  thing  as  the 
subject,  or  the  case  of  negative  propositions,  that 
the  subject  and  predicate  are  not  names  for  the 
same  thing.  He  is  careful,  however,  to  mitigate 
the  extreme  nominalism  of  this  account  by  add 
ing  that  the  use  of  the  copula  in  English  is  to 
make  us  think  of  a  reason  why  the  two  names 
are  both  given  to  the  same  thing.  Searching 
criticism  might  here  find  an  occasion  for  attack 
ing  Hobbes  out  of  his  own  mouth,  since  this  last 
remark  as  to  the  function  of  the  copula  clearly 
sets  limits  to  the  alleged  arbitrariness  of  the  em- 
37 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

ployment,  if  not  to  the  arbitrariness  of  the  inven 
tion,  of  names. 

Keasoning  now  receives  an  equally  nominalist 
definition.  It  is,  and  the  phrase  sounds  curiously 
prophetic  of  the  modern  discovery  that  logic  is 
really  a  mathematical  calculus,  the  computation 
of  the  consequences  of  names,  and  may  be  re 
garded  as  consisting  entirely  of  addition  (the 
formation  of  complex  concepts  by  putting  words 
together),  and  subtraction  (i.e.  abstraction,  the 
formation  of  more  general  concepts  by  analysis  of 
a  complex  name  into  its  simpler  components), 
Concerning  Body,  i.  2,  3 ;  iv.  6 ;  Leviathan,  c.  iv.). 

Now  apart  from  any  minor  objections  which 
might  be  raised  as  to  Hobbes's  tacitly  implied 
theory  of  the  way  in  which  language  has  histori 
cally  developed,  this  whole  account  of  the  nature 
of  reasoning  involves  an  obvious  and  tremendous 
difficulty  of  principle,  a  difficulty  which  meets  us 
again  in  the  doctrine  of  those  modern  mathema 
ticians  and  logicians  who  regard  the  written  or 
printed  symbols  of  Arithmetic  and  Algebra  as  the 
actual  objects  with  which  mathematical  thought 
is  concerned.  As  we  have  seen,  Hobbes  holds 
that  the  whole  body  of  the  conclusions  of  deduc 
tive  science  is  a  mere  consequence  of  the  initial 
deiinitions  (a  point  on  which  he  was  afterwards 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  M 

followed  by  Locke),  and,  as  he  is  careful  ^  point 
out,  the  sense  which  the  introducer  of  a  new 
word  or  other  symbol  is  to  put  upon  his  invention 
is  a  matter  of  his  own  choice.  The  definition, 
then,  being  merely  a  declaration  of  the  sense  in 
which  I  intend  to  employ  a  hitherto  unused  word 
or  other  sign,  is,  properly  speaking,  neither  true 
nor  false.  As  Hobbes  himself  puts  it  (Concerning 
Body,  vi.  15),  it  is  not  necessary  to  dispute  whether 
definitions  are  to  be  admitted  or  no.  For  when  a 
master  is  instructing  his  scholar,  if  the  scholar 
understand  all  the  parts  of  the  thing  defined 
which  are  resolved  in  the  definition,  and  yet  will 
not  admit  of  the  definition, '  there  needs  no  further 
controversy  betwixt  them,  it  being  all  one  as  if 
he  refused  to  be  taught.'  Since  all  our  conclu- 
sions,  then,  are  simply  logical  consequences  of 
arbitrarily  constructed  definitions,  whio.h  are 
themselves  neither  true  nor  false,  it  would  seem 
to  follow  that  the  whole  of  knowledge  is  a  mere 
ingenious  sporting  with  puzzles,  like  the  solving 
of  chess  problems,  the  ultimate  rules  of  the  game 
being,  like  the  rules  of  chess,  neither  true  nor 
false,  but  purely  arbitrary.  In  what  intelligible 
sense,  then,  can  our  conclusions  be  said  to  be 
themselves  true  ? 

It  is  this  difficulty  which  Leibniz  has  in  his 

39 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

mind  when  he  urges  against  the  extreme  nomi 
nalists  that  though  names  are  artificial,  they  are 
not  arbitrary.  (For  instance,  quite  different 
symbols  might  be  chosen  to  represent  the  con 
cepts  we  commonly  symbolise  by  the  signs  2,  3,  5, 
4- ,  = ,  and  in  that  case  the  truth  we  now  write  in 
the  form  2  +  3  =  5  would  be  expressed  by  a  very 
different  set  of  symbols.  But  the  numerical  truth 
meant,  or  symbolised,  by  both  groups  of  signs 
would  be  one  and  the  same.  For  every  true 
proposition,  expressed  in  our  familiar  notation, 
about  relations  between  numbers,  there  would  be 
one,  and  only  one,  corresponding  proposition  in 
the  other  set  of  symbols.  The  particular  signs 
selected  to  denote  the  different  numbers,  and  the 
different  operations  which  can  be  performed  upon 
them,  may  be  largely  arbitrary,  but  there  is 
nothing  arbitrary  about  the  laws  of  their  com 
bination.) 

The  secret  of  Hobbes's  mistake,  in  fact,  lies  in 
the  insidious  error  into  which  he  falls  about  the 
logical  character  and  function  of  definitions.  It 
is  not  true,  as  he  supposes,  that  e.g.  in  Geometry 
the  definitions  are  the  real  premisses  from  which 
the  theorems  are  inferred.  Technically,  as  Hobbes 
himself  has  seen,  a  definition  is  a  mere  verbal 
abbreviation,  a  mere  substitution  of  a  single 
40 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

hitherto  unemployed  word,  or  other  symbol,  for  a 
more  complicated  set  of  words  or  signs  of  already 
known  import.  Hence  you  could  eliminate  the 
definitions  from  the  science  altogether  by  merely 
replacing  every  defined  symbol  in  a  demonstration 
by  the  group  of  symbols  for  which,  as  its  definition 
declares,  it  is  an  abbreviation.  The  only  differ 
ence  such  a  proceeding  would  make  would  be  that 
our  demonstrations  would  be  thus  rendered  pain 
fully  long  and  cumbrous.  This  is  why  Hobbes  is 
perfectly  correct  in  holding  that  a  scientific  defi 
nition  is  really  neither  true  nor  false,  since  it  is, 
in  fact,  not  a  proposition  at  all,  but  a  mere  con 
vention  between  different  thinkers  as  to  the  sense 
to  be  put  on  a  particular  abbreviation.  But  what 
Hobbes  does  not  see  is  thatvjt  follows  at  once  from 
this  correct  view  of  the  function  of  definitions, 
that  the  definitions  are  never  the  premisses  from 
which  our  scientific  demonstrations  are  inferred. 


real  premisses  of  all  demonstrations  are  party 
logical  axioms,  that  is  assertions  which  declare 
that  certain  propositions  imply  formally  the  truth 
of  certain  others,  partly  postulates,  or  unprovable 
existence-theorems,  that  is  assertions  that  certain 
objects  exist,  or  have  a  certain  relation  to  one 
another.  An  instance  of  the  former  kind  of 
premiss  in  Euclid  is  the  'first  axiom,'  which 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

states  that  if  the  magnitude  of  a  is  the  same  as 
that  of  6,  and  the  magnitude  of  b  is  the  same  as 
that  of  c,  then  it  follows  that  the  magnitude  of  a 
is  the  same  as  that  of  c.  Examples  of  the  second 
kind  are  the  unexpressed  postulate  that  there 
exists  the  class  of  entities  called  points,  or  the 
explicitly  enunciated  postulate  of  the  existence  of 
the  straight  line  (i.e.  of  an  entity  which  is  com 
pletely  determined  when  two  of  its  points  are 
given).  And  when  we  carry  our  analysis  of  the 
presuppositions  of  demonstrative  science  far 
enough  we  shall  always  find  that  just  as  the 
ultimate  logical  axioms  are,  for  the  simple  reason 
that  they  are  preconditions  of  all  proof,  them 
selves  unprovable,  so  the  ultimate  existential 
postulates,  because  they  are  preconditions  of  all 
definition,  are  all  assertions  of  the  existence  of 
kinds  of  entities  which  are  indefinable.  Now 
these  ultimate  axioms  and  postulates  being  thus 
neither  arbitrary,  nor  mere  declarations  of  the 
signification  of  names,  we  escape  the  conclusion  to 
which  Hobbes's  view  would  lead,  that  there  is,  in 
the  end,  no  sense  in  asking  whether  the  proposi 
tions  of  science  are  true  or  not,  and  science  comes, 
after  all,  to  be  something  very  different  in  kind 
from  a  curiously  complicated  chess  problem. 
To  return,  however,  to  the  exposition  of  Hobbes's 
42 


PHILOSOPHY,  IT  METHODS 

thought.  As  we  have  aireau^  *v^,  ^obbes  starts 
with  the  assumption,  as  ultimate  scientific  pos 
tulates,  of  the  fundamental  propositions  of  a  rigid 
mechanical  materialism.  The  only  things  which 
we  really  know  to  exist  are  bodies,  and  bodies  are 
only  known  to  us  as  vehicles  of  motion.  All  the 
facts  of  external  nature  and  of  mental  life  must 
therefore,  for  science,  be  varieties  of  motion  in 
the  parts  of  body,  and  nothing  more.  Hence  a 
completed  philosophy  would  amount  to  a  vast 
system  of  deductions  by  which  all  the  truths  of 
physical  and  mental  science  would  be  shown  to 
be  logical  consequences  of  the  ultimate  simple 
laws  of  motion  laid  down  by  mechanics.  From  , 
the  purely  philosophical  point  of  view,  it  is 
Hobbes's  chief  merit  that  he  has  undertaken  the 
task  of  performing  such  a  deduction  with  greater 
consistency,  and  a  fuller  consciousness  of  what  it 
implies  than  any  writer  before  or  after  him ;  he  is 
the  one  consistent  philosophical  materialist  in  the 
history  of  thought,  as  far  as  that  history  is  known 
to  us,  whose  intelligence  rises  above  mediocrity, 
and  whose  candour,  at  the  same  time,  leaves  no 
doubt  as  to  his  exact  meaning.  Hence  it  is  most 
instructive,  as  throwing  light  upon  the  inherent 
defects  of  materialism  as  an  ultimate  philosophical 
standpoint,  to  observe  at  what  points  his  initial 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

postulates  fail  him.  Such  a  failure  occurs,  with 
the  consequence  that  Hobbes  is  forced  to  abandon 
his  strictly  deductive  method,  at  two  critical 
points  in  his  exposition.  When  he  enters  upon 
the  realm  of  our  inner  mental  life  in  his  account 
of  sensation,  he  has  to  abandon  the  attempt  to 
deduce  our  perception  of  the  various  qualities  of 
bodies,  their  colours,  savours,  odours,  and  the  like, 
from  a  mathematical  theory  of  the  external  motions 
which  are  commonly  called  their  causes  or  stimuli, 
and  to  accept  the  correlation  of  the  various  sense- 
qualities  with  certain  external  stimuli  simply  as 
given  and  unexplained  facts  of  experience.  And  in 
the  same  way,  when  he  advances  to  the  theory  of 
human  conduct,  he  finds  it  quite  out  of  the  ques 
tion  to  exhibit  the  fundamental  passions  of  human 
nature  as  movements  of  particles  within  the 
organism  mechanically  determined  by  similar 
movements  on  the  part  of  external  bodies;  the 
fundamental  passions,  like  the  simple,  sensible 
qualities  of  things,  have  to  be  treated  as  unex 
plained  given  facts,  and  the  assertion  that  they  are 
really  motions  of  particles  of  the  body,  and  nothing 
more,  remains  a  mere  unproved  assertion  which 
is  of  no  significance  for  the  further  development 
of  Hobbes's  ethical  scheme.  There  is  thus  no 
real  logical  connection  between  Hobbes's  ineta- 
44 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

physical  materialism  and  his  ethical  and  political 
doctrine  of  human  conduct;  the  whole  of  the 
latter  might,  in  fact,  be  equally  well  grafted  upon 
a  pronounced  spiritualistic  metaphysic,  such  as 
that  of  Descartes.  Even  the  rejection  of  the 
doctrine  of  free  wilH§,  in  point  of  fact,  based  upon 
assumed  psycKoIogical  grounds  which  in  no  way 
involve  the  metaphysical  postulate  that  all  exist 
ence  is  bodily ;  in  short,  the  only  advantage  which 
Hobbes  really  derives  from  his  materialism  is 
that  it  furnishes  him  with  a  plausible  excuse  for 
his  refusal  to  take  theology  seriously. 

Of  Hobbes's  theory  of  the  passions  it  will  be 
time  enough  to  speak  in  the  next  chapter.  But 
something  must  be  said  here  of  the  effect  of 
his  materialistic  assumptions  upon  his  doctrine 
of  perception.  It  is  an  immediate  consequence 
of  the  postulate  that  all  physical  change  is 
motion  that  the  various  apparent  sensible  quali 
ties  of  external  bodies  cannot  be  objectively  real. 
Colours,  smells,  and  the  rest  must  be  mere 
'appearances'  within  the  percipient  of  realities, 
which  are,  in  truth,  mere  motions  of  material 
particles— '  All  which  qualities,  called  sensible, 
are  in  the  object  that  causeth  them  but  so  many 
several  motions  of  the  matter,  by  which  it  presseth 
our  organs  diversely'  (Leviathan,  c.  i.).  Hobbes 
45 

* 

1 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

is  thus  at  one  with  Galileo  and  Descartes,  and  the 
rest  of  the  founders  of  modern  mechanical  science 
in  proclaiming  the  doctrine  of  the  c  subjectivity ' 
of  sensible — or,  as  Locke  named  them — secondary 
qualities.  They  are  not  real  attributes  of  external 
things,  but  simply  effects,  produced  by  the  action 
of  external  things  upon  the '  mind '  or  the  '  nervous 
system '  of  the  percipient.  But  Hobbes  does  not 
stop  at  this  point.  As  a  consistent  materialist, 
he  is  bound  to  hold  that  the  mind  or  nervous 
system  is,  like  everything  else,  a  body,  and  con 
sequently  that  the  only  effect  that  can  be  pro 
duced  upon  it  by  any  external  agent  is  the  same 
kind  of  effect  which  one  external  agent  can 
produce  on  another,  a  modification  of  its  previous 
motions.  The  sensible  quality,  e.g.  a  colour,  must 
not  merely  be  a  mere  subjective  effect  of  external 
motion,  it  must  itself,  as  a  subjective  effect,  be  a 
motion,  and  nothing  more.  So  he  adds  immedi 
ately  after  the  words  just  quoted, '  Neither  in  us 
that  are  pressed  are  they  anything  else  but  divers 
motions;  (for  motion  produceth  nothing  but 
motion).'  Thus  we  are  left  to  face  the  paradox 
that  the  whole  world  of  perceived  sensible  quali 
ties  is  an  illusion,  while  there  is  not,  and  on  the 
principles  of  strict  materialism  cannot  possibly 
be,  any  one  to  be  illuded.  Colours,  tones,  smells, 
-  * 


^OSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

tastes,  have  first  been  declared  to  be  subjective 
effects  produced  upon  the  individual  percipient 
by  the  impact  of  particles  themselves  devoid  of 
all  quality;   then,  since  it  has  to  be  recognised 
that,   according   to   materialism,   the   subject  in 
which  these  effects  are  produced  must  be  itself  ^  * 
just  one  collection  of  such  particles  among  others/\  ^ 
it  is  announced  that  the  effects  themselves  cannot^ 
really  be  there.     If  the  average  materialist  stops   v+ 
short   of    enunciating    this    intolerable   paradox,  *  ,< 
it  is  only  because  he  is  so  far  Hobbes's  inferior 
in  logical  power,  or  in  candour,  or  in  both. 

The  conception  of  the  subjectivity  of  sensible 
qualities  is  still  so  commonly  regarded  as  an 
established  result  of  modern  science  that  it  is 
worth  our  while  to  pause  over  it  for  a  few 
moments,  and  to  ask  whether  it  can  be  main 
tained  in  a  form  which  does  not  lead  to  the 
Hobbian  paradox.  Suppose  that  Hobbes  had 
so  far  relaxed  his  materialism  as  to  recognise  A 
the  real  existence  of  immaterial  'states  of  con-  / 
sciousness,'  might  he  not  have  held,  without  any 
paradoxical  consequences,  that  what  we  com 
monly  call  the  secondary  or  sensible  qualities  of 
external  things  are  in  truth  'states  of  our  own 
consciousness,'  which  are  caused  by  the  action 
of  an  external  world  of  bodies  totally  devoid  of 
47 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

quality  ?  Such  a  view  was  widely  current  in  the 
ancient  philosophical  schools,  and  was  revived 
in  Hobbes's  own  day  by  Galileo  and  Descartes, 
from  the  latter  of  whom  it  passed  as  an  almost 
unquestioned  axiom  into  modern  science.  Yet 
it  is  clear,  I  think,  that  the  doctrine  will  not  bear 
serious  examination.  The  very  ground  upon 
which  the  sensible  qualities  are  declared  to  be 
subjective,  to  be  'in  us '  and  not  ' in  the  things 
outside  us,'  is  the  assumption  that  all  the  pro 
cesses  of  the  physical  world,  however  various 
they  may  seem  to  be,  are  in  actual  facf  purely 
mechanical.  If  this  principle  is  true,  it  must 
hold  just  as  much  for  the  living  organism,  which, 
after  all,  is  just  one  body  among  others,  as  for 
everything  else.  The  effects  of  a  stimulus  upon 
the  organism,  whatever  they  may  seem  to  be, 
must  in  reality  be  as  entirely  mechanical  as  the 
stimulus  itself,  as  Hobbes  very  properly  said. 
Even  if  a  colour  or  a  sound  could  be  said  without 
absurdity  to  be  a  'state  of  consciousness,'  the 
principles  of  a  mechanical  philosophy  would 
absolutely  forbid  our  calling  that' state  an  '  effect ' 
\  of  an  external  stimulus.  The  '  effect '  of  the 
stimulus  would  have  to  be  simply  the  ex  hypothesi 
purely  mechanical  changes  induced  by  it  in  the 
nervous  system,  and  with  these  changes  the 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

'  state  of  consciousness '  would  have  really  no 
discoverable  relation  but  the  temporal  relation 
of  simultaneity.  The  whole  of  our  intellectual  life 
would  become,  as  it  has  sometimes  been  called, 
an  '  epiphenomenon,'  a  series  of  events  occurring 
simultaneously  with  certain  mechanical  changes 
in  the  world  of  bodies,  but  standing  absolutely 
outside  the  series  of  causes  and  effects. 

And,  if  we  carried  analysis  a  step  further,  we 
should  at  once  be  confronted  by  a  still  more 
formidable  difficulty.  For  it  would  readily  be 
come  apparent  that,  whatever  sensible  qualities 
may  be,  they  are  certainly  not  '  states '  of  a  mind. 
When,  in  common  parlance,  I  arn  said  to  see  a 
blue  flower,  it  is  really  ridiculous  to  say  that  in 
truth  it  is  my  mind  which  is  blue.  My  judgment 
'  that  flower  is  blue '  may  be  true,  or  it  may  be 
false,  but  in  either  case  one  thing  is  quite  clear. 
It  is  not  '  being  blue/  but  '  believing  that  the 
(•'•'.*rer  is  blue'  which  is,  in  that  moment,  a  state 
'  :ny  perceiving  mind.  And  this  simple  reflec 
tion  is  in  itself  enough  to  dispose  of  the  whole 
doctrine  of  the  'subjectivity  of  sensible  qualities.' 
There  are  really  only  two  alternative  possibilities 
in  the  case.  Either  all  the  propositions  in  which 
a  sensible  quality  is  ascribed  to  a  thing  are  merely 
false,  as  Hobbes's  account  logically  implies,  or 
D  49 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

slse  there  are  at  least  some  bodies  which  really 

lave  the  sensible  qualities  of  colour,  savour,  and 

50  forth.    It  would  be  no  way  of  escape  to  suggest 

,hat  perhaps  what  is  really  blue  is  neither  the 

lower  nor  my  mind,  but  some  part  of  my  optical 

ipparatus,  e.g.  the  stimulated  region  of  my  retina. 

Tor,  on  such  a  theory,  there  is  at  least  one  body 

vhich   really  has  the   sensible   quality,  viz.  my 

etina.     But,  if  so,  why  not  other  bodies  as  well, 

,nd  what  becomes  of  the  postulate  that  the  only 

objectively  real  properties  of  body  are  mechanical? 

The  fact  is  that  Hobbes,  like  all  the  philo- 

ophers  who   have    taught    the    subjectivity  of 

ensible   qualities,  commits  the  grave  error  of 

rying  to  combine  two   really  inconsistent  con- 

eptions  of  the    relation  between   the  external 

rorld  and  our  perception.     He   tries   to   think 

f  the  world  of  bodies  as  being  at  once  the  cause  : , 

I  perception,  I  and  also  the  object  which  percep- 

ion  apprehends,  j  What  our  last  two  paragraphs 

ave  gone  to  show  is  that  both  these  conceptions 

annot  be  true  at  once.     If  the  external  world  \ 

is  the  cause  of  perception,  it  cannot  be  the  object  \ 

apprehended  in  perception;   in  fact,  perception,^) 

in  that  case,  can  have  no  object  at  all,  and  all 

supposed  knowledge  about  anything  must  be  a 

mere  illusion,  as  was  pretty  clearly  seen  by  Hume. 

So 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

On  the  other  hand,  since  the  external  world  is 
certainly  the  object  of  our  perception  (how  far 
that  perception  is  correct  or  erroneous  makes 
no  difference  to  the  argument),  the  relation  of 
the  world  to  the  perceiving  subject  cannot  pos 
sibly  be  a  causal    one.    When   we    have    once 
grasped  this  truth,  we  shall  see  that  the  accuracy 
of  our  perception  of  sensible   qualities  of  body 
is  a  question  to  be  argued,  in  every  special  case, 
on  its  own  merits,  and  cannot  be  impugned  by 
any  general  a  priori  arguments  drawn  from  the 
principle  of  causality.     Nor  does  this  conclusion 
in  any  way  conflict  with  the  fullest  recognition 
of  the   right   of    physical    science   to   treat   the 
external  world,  for  its  own  purposes,  as  if  it  were 
devoid  of  sensible  qualities,  and  consisted  merely, 
let  us  say,  of  vibratory  motions  of  different  rates 
of  frequency.     All  that  is  required  to  justify  such 
a  proceeding  is  that  there  should  be  a  uniform 
one-to-one    correlation    between     each    sensible 
quality  (e.g.  each  shade  of  colour),  and  a  par 
ticular  kind  of  vibration ;  we  may  then  treat  the 
colour,  for  all  purposes  of  mathematical  physics, 
as  if  it  actually  were  the  vibration,  just  as,  in 
ordinary   analytical   geometry,  we    can    treat    a 
point  in  a  plane  as  if  it  were  actually  a  couple 
of  numbers.    Where  the  physicist  so  often  goes 
Si 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

wrong,  when  he  strays  into  the  domain  of  philo 
sophy,  is  in  hastily  assuming  that  two  things 
which  have  a  one-one  correspondence  to  each 
other  are  really  the  same  thing.  As  for  the 
further  a  posteriori  arguments  by  which  Hobbes 
tries  to  establish  the  subjectivity  of  sense- 
qualities,  e.g.  in  the  first  chapter  of  Leviathan, 
they  are  all  of  the  type  since  made  familiar  by 
Berkeley  and  his  followers  (appeals  to  dreams, 
to  hallucinations,  etc.).  Their  conclusive  force, 
whatever  it  may  be,  would  be  equally  great  if 
we  applied  them  to  the  'primary'  mechanical 
properties  of  body,  or  even  to  Hobbes's  supreme 
reality,  motion  itself,  since  all  these  may  be  the 
subject  of  dreams  and  hallucinations,  just  as 
colours  or  smells  might  be.  In  truth,  all  that 
is  proved  by  arguments  of  this  type  would  seem 
to  be  that  it  is  possible  to  make  erroneous 
judgments  about  external  things,  a  proposition 
which  no  sober  philosophy  is  called  on  to  deny. 

In  one  respect  Hobbes  goes  beyond  most  of  the 
English  writers  who  have  since  espoused  the 
doctrine  that  sensible  qualities  are  subjective ;  he 
maintains  the  same  thing  about  space  and  time  / 
themselves.  They  also  are  merely  'phantasms,' 
that  is,  they  are  not  '  the  accident  or  affection  of 
any  body ' ;  they  are  '  not  in  the  things  without  us, 
52 


PHILOSOPHY,  ITS  SCOPE  AND  METHODS 

but  only  in  the  thought  of  the  mind '  (Concerning 
Body,  vii.  3).  More  precisely,  space  is  '  the  phan 
tasm  of  a  thing  existing  without  the  mind  simply ; 
that  is  to  say,  that  phantasm  in  which  we  con 
sider  no  other  accident,  but  only  that  it  appears 
without  us ' ;  time  is  '  the  phantasm  of  before  and 
after  in  motion'  (Ibid.,  vii.  2,  3).  The  ground 
given  by  Hobbes  for  this  assertion  is  that  if  the 
whole  world  could  be  suddenly  annihilated  except 
one  man,  that  man  would  still  retain  his  con 
sciousness  of  space  and  time.  I  confess  I  do  not 
see  that  this  consideration  proves  anything,  except 
perhaps  that  space  and  time  are  not  bodies,  nor 
do  I  see  how  Hobbes  could  think  that  motion  (the 
successive  occupation  of  different  positions  by  the 
same  thing),  is  objectively  real,  and  yet  hold  that 
space  and  time  are  mere  subjective  ideas  of  our 
own.  His  statement,  it  should  be  noted,  bears  no 
real  resemblance  to  Kant's  famous  doctrine  of  the 
'  ideality '  of  the  forms  of  perception.  Space  and 
time  are  regarded  by  him  not  as  universal  forms 
of  perception  impressed  by  the  mind  upon  a 
'manifold'  of  sensations  received  from  without, 
but  merely  as  constituent  elements  of  the  '  mani 
fold'  itself.  The  whole  distinction  between  a 
formal  element  in  perception,  which  comes  from 
the  perceiving  subject,  and  a  material  element 
53 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

contributed  by  the  external  world,  belongs  to  a 
later  and  more  developed  stage  of  the  theory  of 
knowledge.  It  is,  indeed,  a  signal  advance  upon 
the  Kantian  position  to  recognise  clearly  that  the 
'formal'  element  in  perception  is  no  less  objec 
tive  than  the  *  material,'  but  the  recognition  seems 
inconsistent  with  sensationalism  as  a  theory  of 
knowledge.  Hobbes  is  able  to  be  consistently 
sensationalist  precisely  because  it  does  not  occur 
to  him  to  draw  any  distinction  between  the 
'  formal '  and  the  '  material '  in  our  knowledge. 


54 


CHAPTER    III 

EMPIRICAL  PSYCHOLOGY  —  THE   NATURE   OF   MAN 

WE  may  now  proceed  to  consider  the  main  out 
lines  of  the  analysis  of  cognition  and  volition 
which  has  earned  for  Hobbes  the  well-  merited  title 
of  'founder  of  e,rppirip.ql  psychology.'  that  chief 
contribution  of  the  English-speaking  peoples  to 
mental  science.  This  analysis  will  be  found  by 
the  English  reader  most  fully  set  forth  in  two 
works,  the  Human  Nature  (the  first  part  of  the 
treatise  on  the  Elements  of  Law  originally  com 
posed  in  1640),  and  the  opening  chapters  of 
Leviathan  (published  in  1651).  We  must  bear  in 
mind,  however,  that  Hobbes  is  chiefly  interested 
in  the  ho  of  the  individual  mind  less  for 


its^  own  sake  thanbecause  it  furnishes  him  with 
a  logical  foundation  for  his  naturalistic  docjJjBp 
of  ethics  and  politics;  his  psychology  is  con 
sequently  only  worked  out  so  far  as  is  necessary 
for  the  achievement  of  this  ulterior  end. 

Hobbes,  as  we  have  seen,  does  not  attempt  to 
55 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

deduce  the  principles  of  psychology,  let  alone 
these  of  ethics  and  politics,  from  the  general 
doctrine  of  motion,  but  falls  back  upon  our 
immediate  experience  of  the  main  facts  of  human 
nature  as  we  find  them  in  ourselves.  He  is,  so  to 
say,  an  empiricist  malgre  lui,  and  it  is  one  of  the 
entertaining  ironies  of  history  that  the  English 
philosopher  who,  of  all  others,  is  most  strongly 
insistent  upon  the  deductive  character  of  genuine 
science  should  be  chiefly  remembered  by  that 
part  of  his  work  which  is  most  flagrantly  inconsis 
tent  with  his  own  conception  of  strictly  scientific 
method.  From  the  axiom  that  neither  within  nor 
without  is  there  any  reality  but  motion  there  is, 
in  truth,  no  road  to  moral  and  political  science. 

Hobbes  starts,  in  his  doctrine  of  man,  from  the 
usual  empiricist  assumption  that  all  mental  life 
is  a  development  from  beginnings  in  sensation  \_ 
'  for  there  is  no  conception  in  a  man's  mind  which 
hath  not,  at  first,  totally  or  by  parts,  been  be 
gotten  upon  the  organs  of  sense.  The  rest  are 
derived  from  that  original'  (Leviathan,  c.  i.). 
Sensation,  as  we  have  seen,  is,  according  to  him, 
a  motion  caused  in  these  organs  by  previous 
Liotion  in  some  external  body.  Why  the  sensible 
qualities,  thus  begotten,  are  supposed  to  belong  to 
external  bodies  he  explains  by  the  theory  that  all 
56 


EMPIRICAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

sensation  gives  rise  to  motor  reaction  from  the 
heart,  which  he,  like  the  Aristotelians,  regards  as 
the  centre  of  the  nervous  system,  towards  the 
periphery  of  the  body.  It  is  the  outward-flowing 
direction  of  these  reactions  which  causes  sensible 
objects  to  appear  without  us,  —  a  crude  version  of 
the  now  seriously  discredited  doctrine  of  '  feelings 
of  innervation.'  He  immediately  adds  a  doctrine 
of  the  relativity  of  sensation.  Sensation  requires 
a  constant  variety  of  stimuli  ;  persistent  exposure 
to  an  unvarying  stimulus  would  readily  give  rise 
to  total  unconsciousness,  '  it  being  almost  one  for  a 
man  to  be  always  sensible  of  one  and  the  same  thing 
and  not  to  be  sensible  at  all  of  anything  '  (Cone*,  n 
ing  Body,  xxv.  5).  That  is,  consciousness  depends 
.  From  sensation  Hobbes  goes  on 


next  to  derive  imagination  and  memory.  Im 
agination  is  simply  '  decaying  sense/  i.e.  the  per 
sistence,  in  a  less  intense  form,  of  the  organic 
process  excited  by  a  stimulus  after  the  stimulus 
itself  has  been  withdrawn.  This  persistence  itself, 
again,  is  a  consequence  of  what  Newton  was  after 
wards  to  call  the  '  first  law  of  motion/  '  When  a 
body  is  once  in  motion,  it  moveth  (unless  some 
thing  else  hinder  it)  eternally,  and  whatsoever  hin- 
dereth  it,  cannot  in  an  instant,  but  in  time,  and  by 
degrees  quite  extinguish  it.  And  as  we  see  in  the 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

water,  though  the  winds  cease,  the  waves  give  not 
over  rolling  for  a  long  time  after;  so  also  it 
happeneth  in  that  motion  which  is  made  in  the 
internal  parts  of  a  man,  ther\  when  he  sees, 
dreams,  etc.  For  after  the  object  is  removed,  or 
the  eye  shut,  we  still  retain  an  image  of  the 
"  thing  seen,  though  more  obscure  than  when  we 
see  it.  ...  Imagination  therefore  is  nothing  but 
decaying  sense'  (Leviathan,  c.  ii.).  How,  in  the 
general  subjectivity  of  all  sensation,  we  are  to 
\  know  whether  the  'object5  has  really  been  'with- 
Jp  drawn '  or  not  is  a  problem  which  Hobbes  would 
scarcely  have  found  it  easy  to  solve.  Memory  is 
nc";v  explained  to  be  simply  imagination  of  what 
is  past.  '  When  we  would  express  the  decay,  and 
signify  that  the  sense  is  fading,  old,  and  past,  it  is 
called  Memory.  So  that  imagination  and  memory 
are  but  one  thing,  which  for  divers  considerations 
hath  divers  names '  (Ib.). 

It  is  clear  that  we  are  here  again  confronted  by 
a  difficulty  which  Hobbes's  superficial  appeals  to 
physical  analogies  cannot  conceal.  For  imagina 
tion  is  by  no  means  exclusively  of  things  past ; 
we  can  imagine  our  future  as  readily  as  we  can 
remember  our  past,  and  we  often  divert  ourselves 
by  imagining  a  state  of  things  which  neither  has 
existed  nor  will  ever  exist.  Now  how  do  we 
58 


EMPIRICAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

come  to  make  these  distinctions  between  different 
imaginations  if  imagination  and  memory  are 
merely  two  names  for  the  same  thing  looked  at 
from  two  different  points  of  view  ?  Why  is  not 
all  imagination  indistinguishable  from  reminis 
cence  ?  In  other  words,  what  a  psychological 
analysis  of  memory  ought  to  account  for  is  not 
the  mere  fact  thatwe  can  imagine  what  is 
actually  past,  but  the  fact  that,  in  doing  so,  we 
recognise  the  events  imagined  as  belonging  to 
the  past  and  not  to  the  future  or  to  no  time 
at  all.  The  secret  of  Hobbes's  failure  to  give  any 
satisfactory  account  of  memory  is  not  hard  to 
find,  and  it  is  also  the  secret  of  much  more  that 
is  defective  in  his  psychological  analysis.  What 
must  happen  to  any  really  consistent  sensationalist 
in  psychology  has  happened  to  him.  In  his 
derivation  of  mental  life  from  passively  received 
sensations  he  has  forgotten  the  presence  of  .selec 
tive  attention  as  an  ever-present  factor  which 
actively  determines  the  course  of  all  mental  pro 
cesses.  It  is  only  when  we  have  learned  to 
distinguish  that  from  which  attention  is  turning 
away  from  that  towards  which  it  is  moving  that 
we  acquire  a  basis  for  the  distinction  between  im 
agination  of  what  is  '  no  longer '  and  imagination 
of  what  is  '  not  yet.' 

59 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

Hobbes  next  advances  to  the  analysis  of  com 
plex  trains  of  thought  (Leviathan,  c.  iii.).  He 
begins  by  laying  down  the  general  doctrine  of 
'  association  of  ideas/  giving  a  crude  account  of  the 
psycho-physical  dependence  of  the  process  upon  the 
formation  of '  paths  of  conduction  '  in  the  nervous 
system,  and  recognising '  association  by  contiguity 
'more  explicitly  than  '  association  by  resemblance/ 
though  the  latter  is  not  entirely  overlooked. 
'  When  a  man  thinketh  on  anything  whatsoever, 
his  next  thought  after  is  not  altogether  so  casual 
as  it  seems  to  be.  Not  every  thought  to  every 
thought  succeeds  indifferently.  But  ...  we  have 
no  transition  from  one  imagination  to  another 
whereof  we  never  hacl  the  like  before  in  our 
senses.  The  reason  whereof  is  this.  All  fancies 
are  motions  within  us/ relics  of  those  made  in 
the  sense ;  and  "those  motions  that1  immediately 
succeeded  one  another  in  the  sense  continue  also 
together  after  sense,  insomuch  as  the  former  coming 
again  to  take  place  and  be  predominant,  the  later 
followeth  by  coherence  of  the  matter  moved/ 
He  distinguishes,  however,  between  mere  random 
association  and  thought  guided  or  regulated  by 
the  presence  of  a  definite  end  or  purpose  which 
controls  the  formation  of  associations,  e.g.  the 
orderly  thinking  out  of  a  series  of  steps  towards 
60 


> 

EMPIRICAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

the  gratification  of  a  given  desire.  This  latter 
ought  really  to  present  a  difficulty  to  him,  since 
it  most  obviously  involves  the  presence  of  pur 
posive  attention  as  actively  determining  the 
current  of  thought,  and  leading  to  sequences  in 
'imagination'  quite  independent  of  previous 
sequences  '  in  our  senses,'  and  it  seems  manifest 
that  such  attention  cannot  be  analysed  into  a 
mere  succession  of  subjective  effects  of  physical 
stimuli.  On  Hobbes's  theory,  as  on  any  theory 
which  treats  association  as  more  than  a  sub 
ordinate  factor  in  determining  the  course  of 
thought,  whenever  we  think  of  a  given  thing  A, 
.  our  next  thought  should  be  of  a  thing  B,  which 
^is  either  very  like  A  or  has  been  most  commonly 
perceived  or  thought  of  in  close  connection  with 
A.  In  actual  fact,  in  proportion  as  our  thinking 
is  truly  rational,  or,  as  Hobbes  would  say,  regu 
lated,  the  B  which  the  thought  of  A  calls  up  is 
that  which  it  is  most  relevant  to  our  present 
object  to  think  of  next,  and  this  B  may  be  some 
thing  quite  unlike  A  and  something  which  has 
never  been  thought  of  in  this  particular  con 
nection  with  A  before.  It  is  really  only  un 
regulated,  random  thinking  which  is  dominated 
by~  association ;  in  an  orderly  train  of  pur- 
2sive  thinking  association  appears,  as  often  as 
61 


1 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

not,   as  a  disturbing  factor  and  source   of  pure 
irrelevance. 

Hobbes  now  proceeds  (Leviathan,  c.  vi.)  to  a 
similar  analysis  of  voluntary  motions,  i.e.  the 
whole  conative  side  of  mental  life.  Like  most 
pre-Kantian  psychologists  he  reckons  feeling  and 
emotion  among  the  forms  of  conation.  Conation^ 
is,  in  every  case,  nothing  but  incipient  motion 
within  the  nervous  system,  and  such  incipient 
outward-directed  reaction  Hobbes  calls  by  the 
general  name  endeavour.  Endeavour,  again,  has 
two  contrasted  directions.  It  iselther  endeavour 
to  or  from  a  perceived  object,  the  words  '  to '  and 
from '  being  understood  quite  literally  of  direc 
tion  in  space.  Endeavour  towards  an  object  is 
what  we  call  appetite  or  desire ;  endeavour  "from 
an  object  is  called  aversion.  Other  names  for 
the  two  directions  of  endeavour  are  love  and  hate. 
1  Because  going,  speaking,  and  the  like  voluntary 
motions  depend  always  upon  a  precedent  thought 
of  whither,  which  way,  and  what,  it  Js^evident 
tlyitlLLgjniagination  is  the  first  internal  beginning 
of  all  voluntary  motions^  And.  althougl 
"Studied  men  do  not  conceive  any  motion  at  all 
to  be  there,  where  the  thing  moved  is  invisible, 
or  the  space  it  is  moved  in  is  (for  the  shortness 
of  it)  insensible;  yet  that  doth  not  hinder  bn'fi 
62 


EMPIRICAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

that  such  motions  are.  .  .  .  These  small  beginnings 
of  motion,  within  the  body  of  man,  before  they 
appear  in  walking,  speaking,  striking,  and  other 
visible  actions,  are  commonly  called  ENDEAVOUR. 
This  endeavour,  when  it  is  toward  something 
which  causes  it,  is  called  APPETITE,  or  DESIRE; 
.  .  .  and  when  the  endeavour  is  fromward  some 
thing,  it  is  generally  called  AVERSION.  .  .  .  That 
which  men  desire,  they  are  also  said  to  LOVE,  and 
to  HATE  those  things  for  which  they  have  aversion. 
So  that  desire  and  love  are  the  same  thing ;  save 
that  by  desire  we  always  signify  the  absence  of 
the  object,  by  love  most  commonly  the  presence 
of  the  same.  So  also  by  aversion  we  signify  the 
absence,  and  by  hate  the  presence,  of  the  object' 
(76.,  c.  vi.). 

Whatever  is   the  object  of  appetite  or  desire 

f  to  a  man  he  calls  good;  whatever  is  the  object  o£ 

f  aversion  he  calls  evil.    Hence,  since  the  desires 

'  of  different  men,  and  even  of  the  same  man  at 

different  times,  are  very  various,  good  and  evil 

\    are  purely  relative  terms,  and  there  can  be  no 

common  measure  of  them,  except  in  civil  society, 

where  they  are  determined  by  the  command  of 

the  ruler ;  hence,  again,  the  absolute  necessity  for 

the  civil  sovereign  and  his  laws,  if  moral  anarchy 

v  is   to   be  avoided.      '  These  words  .  .  .  are  ever 

]  63 

i 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

used  with  relation  to  the  person  that  useth  thei^ , 
there  being  nothing  simply  and  absolutely  so,  nor 
any  common  rule  of  good  and  evil  to  be  taken 
from  the  nature  of  the  objects  themselves,  but 
from  the  person  of  the  man  (when  there  is  no 
commonwealth),  or  (in  a  commonwealth)  from 
the  person  that  representeth  it,  or  from  an 
I  arbitrator  or  judge,  whom  men  disagreeing  shall 
by  consent  set  up,  and  make  his  sentence  the 
rule  thereof  (Leviathan,  c.  vi.).  In  other  words, 
there  is  no  such  thing  as  a  moral  law,  equally 
binding  upon  all  persons,  except  in  an  organised 
political  community,  and  in  such  a  community  it 
self  what  we  call  the  '  moral '  law  is  a  consequence, 
a  reflex  in  the  consciousness  of  the  individual  man, 

of  the  habit  of  obedience  to  the  commands  of  a/ 

>»c 
political  ruler. 

It  follows  from  this  purely  naturalistic  con 
ception  of  the  primary  meaning  of  the  words 
'  good '  and  '  evil/  that  '  of  the  voluntary  acts  of 
every  man  the  object  is  some  good  to  himself 
(76.,  c.  xiv.).  The  proposition  is,  in  fact,  tauto- 
logous,  since,  according  to  Hobbes's  definition  of 
good,  good  means  what  a  man  desires,  and,  as 
we  are  to  see  immediately,  his  psychology  is 
unable  to  draw  any  real  distinction  between 
desire,  or  '  appetite/  and  volition.  Thus,  on  the 
64 


EMPIRICAL  PSYCH 

ground  that  'the  object  of  a  man* 
object  of  his  desire/  Hobbes  bases  the  conclusion 
that  all  voluntary  action  is,  in  the  last  resort, 
purely  egoistic,  though  it  appears  that  the  '  good  ' 
at  which  an  action  aims  may,  in  some  cases,  be 
the  suppression  of  the  pain  we  feel  at  the  sight 
of  another  person's  suffering,  and  room  is  thus 
made  for  a  limited  and  rather  inferior  kind  of 
benevolence.  It  should  further  be  noted  that 
Hobbes  oddly  confounds  pleasure  and  pain  with 
the  consciousness  of  appetite  and  of  aversion 
respectively,  a  gross  blunder  in  analysis  which  is 
forced  on  him  by  the  necessity  of  bringing  all 
features  of  our  mental  life  under  one  of  the 


heads,  cognition  and  motor  impulse.  Similarly,^  I 
he  is  obliged  to  falsify  his  analysis  of  deliberation 
and  volition.  Deliberation  is  nothing  more  than 
a  succession  of  alternating  impulses  or  appetites 
towards  and  from  the  same  object.  'When  in 
the  mind  of  man  appetites  and  aversions,  hopes 
and  fears,  concerning  one  and  the  same  thing 
arise  alternately,  and  divers  good  and  evil  con 
sequences  of  the  doing  or  omitting  the  thing 
propounded  come  successively  into  our  thoughts, 
so  that  sometimes  we  have  an  appetite  towards 
it,  sometimes  an  aversion  from  it  ...  the  whole 
Q1H8  °iujJesireQ'  ^aversions,  hopes,  and  fears  con- 

' 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

tinued  till  the  thing  be  either  done,  or  thought 
impossible,  is  that  we  call  DELIBERATION' 
(Leviathan,  c.  vi.).  It  follows,  of  course,  that 
deliberation  is  no  prerogative  of  man,  but  common 
to  him  with  the  '  brutes.5  Will  is  simply  the  last 
member  of  this  series,  the  appetite  or  aversion 
which  immediately  precedes  the  visible  bodily 
reaction.  '  The  last  appetite  or  aversion  immedi 
ately  adhering  to  the  action,  or  to  the  omission 
thereof,  is  that  we  call  the  Will  .  .  .  and  beasts, 
that  have  deliberation,  must  necessarily  also  have 
will '  (lb.). 

From  the  definition  of  good  and  evil,  it  follows 
that  Hobbes  adopts  a  purely  and  crudely  deter- 
ininist  view  on  the  question  of  free  will.  A  man 
inevitably  aims  at  that  which  at  the  moment 
appears  good  to  himself;  in  fact  all  that  we  mean 
by  saying  that  it  appears  good  to  him  is  that  he 
does  so  aim  at  it.  Hobbes's  essay  on  Liberty  and 
Necessity  still  remains  one  of  the  clearest  and 
most  forcible  statements  of  the  case  for  this  kind 
of  rigid  determinism  against  any  admission  of 
j  contingency  or  genuine  freedom  in  human  action. 

This  whole  theory  of  volition  obviously  suffers 

I  from  grave  psychological  defects,  which,  in  their 
turn,  lead  to  equally  grave  ethical  and  sociological 
errors.  The  secret  source  of  Hobbes's  worst 


EMPIRICAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

mistakes  in  ethical  theory  must  be  sought  in  the 
absurd  inadequacy  of  his  analysis  of  deliberation. 
From  the  standpoint  of  a  really  thorough  psy 
chology,  nothing  can  be  more  ludicrous  than  his 
confusion  of  rational  deliberation  with  a  mere 

,  see-saw  of  conflicting  animal  impulses.  Rational 
deliberation,  as  distinguished  from  mere  hesitation, 
implies  the  successive  examination  of  alternative 
possibilities  of  action  with  a  preconceived  plan 
or  purpose  which  Is^jdrelHy^i&xed  in  its  main 

\putlines,  but  receives  further  special  determina 
tion  as  t"o  its  details  by  each  of  these  successive 
comparisons^  the  final  selection  of  one  of  the 
alternatives  as  the  line  to  be  followed  is  an  acfc, 
totally  different  in  its  psychical  character  from : 
the  blind  translation  into  overt  movement  of  anj 
irrational  impulse.  Hence  it  is  that_  we  cant 
actually  desire  what  wgdo  not  will,  and  will  much 
we  do  not  desire.  Thus  we  find  in  Hobbes's 
account  of  volition  precisely  the  same  blindness 
to  the  importance  of  selective  attention  which  we 
had  found  in  his  analysis  of  cognition.  This  has 
a  further  most  momentous  consequence  for  his 
ethical  and  social  doctrine.  From  the  identifica 
tion  of  volition  with  mere  animal  appetite  it 
follows  that  civilisation  can  provide  us  with  no 
new  objects  of  volition,  it  can  merely  increase  our 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

command  over  the  means  of  gratifying  desires 
which  remain  identical  with  those  of  the  savage, 
or  supply  additional  motives,  such  as,  e.g.  fear  of 
the  police  or  the  gallows,  strong  enough  to  check 
the  gratification  of  such  desires.  We  are  all  still 
savages  at  heart,  though  we  are  better  informed 
than  the  savage  as  to  the  probable  consequences 
of  gratifying  our  appetites,  and  have  also  con-  s 
trived  to  attach  artificially  various  new  unpleasant 
consequences  to  the  gratification  of  some  of  them. 
Not,  of  course,  that  Hobbes  was  himself  ethically 
on  the  level  of  a  savage;  the  acquisition  of  a 
rational  comprehension  of  life  to  which  Hobbes's 
labours  were  so  unremittingly  devoted,  is  itself 
an  object  of  desire  impossible  to  a  mere  savage, 
but  for  such  objects  his  crude  psychological 
analysis  has  provided  no  place.  It  is  a  direct 
consequence  of  this  analysis,  and  at  the  same 
time  the  real  foundation  of  his  whole  moral  and 
social  theory,  that  competition  for  objects  of 
desire  which  can  only  be  enjoyed  by  one  man  on 
the  condition  that  all  others  are  prevented  from 
enjoying  them,  is  still,  as  it  always  has  been,  the 
law  of  human  life,  and  that  this  competition  will 
always  make  ordered  society  impossible  unless 
there  is  a  ruler  with  the  admitted  right  to  set 
limits  to  it  and  the  power  to  enforce  his  regula- 
68 


EMPIRICAL   PSYCHOLOGY 

tions  by  penalties.  However  strongly  some  of  the 
facts  of  the  period  of  revolution  through  which 
England  was  passing  during  Hobbes's  manhood 
might  suggest  such  a  conception,  it  should  be 
manifest  to  a  dispassionate  student  of  human 
history  that  it  does  infinitely  less  than  justice  to 
the  extent  to  which,  as  civilisation  advances,  the 
objects  of  human  desire  become  more  and  more 
of  a  non- competitive  kind,  or  of  a  kind  which  are 
positively  unattainable  by  one  man  except  on 
the  condition  of  their  equal  attainment  by  his 
fellows. 

Hobbes  develops  these  portentous  ethical  con 
sequences  of  his  psychology  in  much  detail  in  the 
eleventh  and  thirteenth  chapters  of  Leviathan. 
The  supreme  aim  of  every  man  is  to  obtain 
power,  i.e.  an  assured  command  over  the  means 
of  future  gratification  of  desire,  the  reason  why 
this  passion  persists  so  obstinately  throughout 
life  being  not  so  much  that  man  is  never  content 
with  the  degree  of  satisfaction  he  has  already 
attained,  as  the  uncertainty  whether  he  will 
continue  to  retain  it  undiminished.  '  In  the  first 
place,  I  put  for  a  general  inclination  of  all  man 
kind  a  perpetual  and  restless  desire  of  power  after 
power  that  ceaseth  only  in  death.  And  the  cause 
of  this  is  not  always  that  a  man  hopes  for  a  more 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

intensive  delight, ...  or  that  he  cannot  be  content 
with  a  moderate  power,  but  because  he  cannot 
%  assure  the  power  and  means  to  live  well  which  he 
hath  present  without  the  acquisition  of  more.' 
(Leviathan  c.  xi.) 

Now  Hobbes  also  holds  that  there  ia.no ^great 
natural  difference  between  one  man  and  another 
either  in  physical  or  mental  capacity :  *  As  to  the 
strength  of  body,  the  weakest  has  strength  enough 
to  kill  the  strongest,  either  by  secret  machination 
or  by  confederacy  with  others  that  are  in  the 
same  danger  with  himself.  And  as  to  the  faculties 
of  the  mind  ...  I  find  yet  a  greater  equality 
amongst  men  than  that  of  strength.5  (Ib.,  c.  xiii.). 
Consequently,  the  natural  state  of  man,  i.e.  the 
condition  into  which  he  is  born  and  in  which 
he  remains,  so  far— aa_he  does  not  artificially 
put  an  end  to  ij^  by  iiie  creation  of  a  political 
system,  is  one  of_nniyiersal  competition,  or  as 
Hobbes,  who  likes  to  give  his  ideas  the  most 
startling  and  provocative  wording,  phrases  it,  one 
of  'war  of  every  man  against  every  man,'  in 
which  there  is  no  moral  law,  since  the  recognition 
of  moral  law  is  onlvjpossible  among  men  living  in 
civil  society,  and  respecting  their  mutual  rights 
and  duties.  '  To  this  war  of  every  man  against 
every  man  this  als_o_js  consequent,  that  nothing 
70 


EMPIRICAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

can  be  unjust.     The  notions  of  right  and  wrong, 
justice  and  injustice,  have  there  no  place.    Where 
there  is  no    common  power,   there  is  no   law; 
where  no  law,  no  injustice.     Force  and  fraud  are *• 
in  war  the  two  cardinal  virtues.  ...  It  is.  con 
sequent  also   to   the  same  condition  that  there 
$be  no  propriety  (i.e.  property),  no  dominion,  no 
mine  and   thine   distinct,   but   only  that   to  be 
every  man's  that  he  can  get,  and  for  so  long  as 
he  can  get  keep  it '  (/&•)•     This  state  of  universal 
anarchy,  we  must  remember,  is  not  in  the  least 
Hobbes's  ideal,  as  it  has  sometimes  been  falsely  re 
presented  to  be  by  unscrupulous  controversialists ; 
on  the  contrary,  he  abhors  it,  and  is   at  great 
pains  to  point  out  its  horrors.     So  long  as  it  lasts,  j 
there  can  be  no  settled  industry  or  commerce,  no 
0  science,  no  arts  or  letters,  '  and,  which  is  worst  of 
all,  continuous  fear  and  danger  of  violent  death ; 
and  the  life  of  man,  solitary,  poor,  nasty,  brutish, 
and    short1   (/&.).      The    salvation    of   man,    in    ; 
fact,  as  we  shall  see,  depends  on  the  fact  that 
though    nature    has   placed    him    in    so    evil    a 
condition,   she  has    also    endowed   him   with   '  a 
possibility  to  come  out  of  it.'     Whatever  we  may  V 
think  of  Hobbes's  analysis  ofhuman  nature,  it 
must   not  be  forgotten  for  a  moment   that  itsi 
object  is  not  the  repudiation _of  law  and  morality,! 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

but  the  vindication   of  them  as  the  only  safe 
guards  against  generaLanarchy  and  misery. 

In  proof  of  the  correctness  of  the  dark  picture 
thus  drawn  of  what  human  life  would  be  without 
a  firmly  established  political  authority  to  protect 
men  against  one  another  and  against  their  own 
anti-social  appetites,  Hobbes  appeals  (1)  to  the 
actual  condition  of  savages)  (2)  to  the  absence  of 
all  moral  restraint  shown  in  the  mutual  relations  of 
independent  states,  who  have  no  common  superior, 
towards  each  other;  and  (3),  with  special  refer 
ence  to  the  calumniators  who  charged  him  with 
a  desire  to  undermine  the  authority  of  the  exist 
ing  moral  law,  to  the  precautions  which  men  take 
against  one  another  even  in  settled  and  civilised 
states.  He  thus  fairly  retorts  that  he  only  puts 
into  words  what  is  implied  in  the  conduct  of  his 
critics  themselves  when  they  bar  their  chests, 
lock  their  doors,  or  carry  arms  when  on  a  journey. 

Hobbes's  account  of  the  '  state  of  nature '  is,  of 
course,  as  is  shown  in  particular  by  the  seventeenth 
chapter  of  Leviathan,  expressly  intended  to  con 
tradict  the  doctrine  of  Aristotle,  revived  and  made 
popular  in  his  own  time  by  the  famous  work  of 
Grotius,  De  Jure  Belli  et  Pads,  that  man  is 
'naturally  a  political  animal,'  i.e.  that  the  rudi 
ments  of  sociability  and  social  organisation  are 
72 


EMPIRICAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

never  absent  from  any  group  of  human  beings 
living  together.  This  implies,  contrary  to  Hobbes's 
psychological  analysis,  that  human  impulses  are 
not  exclusively  egoistic.  So  Hobbes  reverts  to  a 
notion  ultimately  derived  from  the  old  Greek 
sophists,  who  taught  that  morality  is  the  result  of 
^convention,'  the  i^ljjm-kh&t  mankind  originally 
existed  in  a  '  state_^L_aature,'  which  was  one  of 
sheer  lawlessness,  and  that_jJI  settled  morality  is 
the  result  of  Ibabituation  to  obedience  to  political 
rules,  which  must  haw  been  originally  set  up  by 
voluntary  agreemejiLjlTLJcontract.  It  is  easy  to 
point  out  that  Hobbes  exaggerates  the  extent  to 
which  morality  is  a  mere  effect  of  civil  obedience, 
and  to  show,  in  the  light  of  later  research,  that 
eveiLsavages,.  who  have  no  settled  political  organi- 
sation,  really  possess  a  rudimentary  morality 
based  on  traditional  tribal  custom.  It  is  equally 
true  that  he  exaggerates  the  defects  even  of  the 
seventeenth  century,  when  he  maintains  that  inde 
pendent  nations  recognise  no  moral  restrictions 
whatever  in  their  dealings  with  their  neighbours. 
Yet  his  reflections  on  the  character  of  international 
morality,  as  well  as  on  the  precautions  taken  even 
by  the  citizen  of  a  law-abiding  community  against 
his  fellows,  retain  even  to-day  a  great  deal  of 
unpleasant  significance.  We  are,  after  all,  in 
73 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

many  things  nearer  the  savage  than  we  like 
to  think,  and  it  is  well  that  we  should  not  be 
allowed  to  forget  the  fact. 

And  it  is,  at  least,  an  important  part  of  the  truth, 
that  our  moral  codes  are  too  largely  merely  the 
effect  of  unreasoned  acquiescence  in  long  estab 
lished  custom,  while  there  can  be  no  doubt  that 
Hobbes  is  much  nearer  the  truth  than  the  senti 
mental  writers  before  and  after  him,  who  have 
glorified  the  relatively  lawless  condition  of  the 
pre-civilised  man  as  a  golden  age  of  superior 
innocence  or  virtue.  And  there  is  an  element  of 
truth  in  Hobbes's  polemic  against  Aristotle's  con 
ception  of  the  way  in  which  the  family  has 
widened  into  the  village  community,  and  the 
village  community  into  the  city  or  nation,  by  a 
process  of  peaceful  expansion.  We  know  enough 
now  of  the  steps  by  which  historical  Greece  came 
into  existence  to  be  sure  that  what  lay  behind  the 
formation  of  the  Greek  polis  was,  more  often 
than  not,  invasion,  conquest,  massacre,  and  the 
anarchy  produced  by  the  violent  subversion  of 
older  settled  '  morality.'  If  we  abandon  the  empty 
dream  of  ever  discovering  historical  information 
as  to  the  '  primitive '  condition  of  mankind,  and 
content  ourselves  with  the  more  modest  question, 
What  state  of  things  preceded  the  growth  of  that 
74 


EMPIRICAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

which  we  call  Western  civilisation,  whether 
Hellenic  or  Germanic,  we  shall  find  that  Hobbes 
has,  after  all,  given  us  a  large  part,  though  not 
the  whole,  of  the  truth,  especially  if  we  take  his 
picture,  with  his  own  qualifying  remark  that '  it 
was  never  generally  so  all  over  the  world/  and 
that  his  prime  purpose  is  not  to  write  ancient 
history,  but  to  show  by  philosophical  analysis 
'  what  manner  of  life  there  would  be  where  there 
were  no  common  power  to  fear,  by  the  manner 
of  life  which  men  that  have  formerly  lived  under 
a  peaceful  government  use  to  degenerate  into  a 
civil  war '  (Leviathan,  c.  xiii.). 


75 


/ 


y 


CHAPTER   IV 

THE   MAKING   OF   THE   LEVIATHAN 

WE  have  seen,  in  the  last  chapter,  what  is 
Hobbes's  conception  of  the  '  state  of  nature,'  the 
condition  in  which  man  found  himself  at  the 
dawn  of  civilisation,  and  into  which  he  tends  to 
degenerate  when  the  bonds  of  political  allegiance 
are  gravely  relaxed.  It  is  a  condition  in  which 
the  machinery  provided  by  government  for  the 
restraint  of  men's  fundamentally  anti-social 
impulses  is  entirely  absent,  and_in  which  there 
is  nothing  to  take  its  place.  ,  How,  then,  could 
any  number  of  men  ever  pass  out  of  this  state  of 
anarchy  into  a  state  of  settled  order  ?  Hobbes 
replies  that  there  is  a  possibility  to  escape  from 
the  state  of  nature  into  one  of  civil  society  which 
is  founded  partly  on  men's  passions,  partly  on 
omen's  reason.  Partly  on  their  passions,  since 
among  these  there  are  several  which  make  for 
peace  and  orderly  existence,  such  as  '  fear  of  death, 
desire  of  such  things  as  are  necessary  to  com- 


MAKING  OF  THE  LEVIATHAN 

modious  living,  and  a  hope  by  their  industry  to 
obtain  them.'  (Leviathan,  c.  xiii.)  Partly  on 
reason^  since;  it  is  reason  which  suggests  to  man 
kind  the  proper  means  of  securing  gratification 
for  these  unbellicose  passions,  or  as  Hobbes  puts 
it,  '  suggesteth  convenient  articles  of  peace  upon 
which  men  may  be  drawn  to  agreement  ''••  (76.). 
We  might,  perhaps,  ask  how  men  living  by  the 
unregulated  promptings  of  egoistic  appetite  ever 
come  to  listen  to  these  'suggestions'  of  reason, 
but  here,  too,  Hobbes  is  ready  with  an  answer. 
We,  all  of  us,  he  says,  have  our  calmer  moments 
when  rational  reflection  is  undisturbed  by  passion,^ 
and  it  is  then  that  the  voice  which  suggests 
'  articles  of  peace  '  makes  itself  heard. 

Like  the  great  majority  of  the  political  theorists 
from  Hooker  in  the  sixteenth  century  to  Kousseau 
in  the  eighteenth,  JFTnfr  frp.R  t.h  n  «  aSELLTT1  ft 
thejransition  from  savagery  to  civil 


the  so-called  {  socjaJLcompact/     Hence  with 
him,  as  with  the  others,  it  becomes  the  first  object 
of  political  theory  to  discover  the  terms  of  this 
original  contract  —  the  '  articles  of  peace  '  alreadv 
mentioned  —  since   it  is  by  these  terms  that  \\ 
have    to    ascertain   the    limits   of    the   rightfi 
authority  of  political  rulers.  <^The  ruler  is  legit 
77 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

raately  entitled  to  just  so  much  authority  over 
his   subjects,  and   no  more,  as  can  be  logically'N 
deduced  from  the  examination  of  the  terms  of  I 
the    contract    by    which    civil    subjection    was  / 
first   instituted.      Whatever   in   the    practice   of/ 
actual  rulers   is   not  covered  by  these  terms  is 
usurpation.     This  method  of  deducing  the  rights 
of  a  government  over  its  subjects  from  a  supposed 
original  contract,  which  had,  in  point  of  fact,  come 
down  to  the  thinkers  of  the  sixteenth  century 
from  the  mediaeval  legists  and  schoolmen,  who 
were  seeking  a  rational   basis   for   their  various 
theories   of  the   division   of  power   between  the 
"Pope  and  the  secular  authorities,  or  between  the 
Pope  and  the  general  councils,  received  its  death 
blow  towards  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  century 
from  Bentham  and  Burke,  both  of  whom  insist, 
in  different  ways,  that  the  rights  of  governments 
must  be  based  on  the  actual  needs  of  society,  and 
k  not  on  any  theory  of  the  primitive  rights  of  man. 
Bentham's  arguments,  which  will  be  found  in  his 
Fragment  on   Government,  are   mainly  directed 
against  Blackstone's  attempt  to   determine    the 
rights  of  the  British  Crown  by  deductions  from 
the  compact  between  king  and  people  supposed 
to    be  made  in    the    coronation    oath,   Burke's, 
against  the  onslaught  of  the  French  Re-volution, 
78 


MAKING  OF  THE  LEVIATHAN 

acting  in  the  name  of  the  '  rights  of  man '  upon 
the  vested  interests,  which  he  chooses  to  regard  as 
established  '  rights/  of  the   nobility  and   clergy. 
In  the  nineteenth  century,  the  growth  of  historical 
research  into  social  origins  made  the  conception 
of  government  as  having  arisen  at  a  definite  time 
by  means  of  a  definite  voluntary  compact  even 
more  unreal,  by  revealing  the  enormous  extent  to 
which  definite  political  institutions  have  arisen 
out  of  an  earlier  stage  of  '  customary '  law.     In 
deed,  when  we  look  the  matter  squarely  in  the 
face,  it  becomes  evident  that  free  association  by 
voluntary  agreement  belongs  to  the  culmination 
rather  than  to  the  beginnings  of  civilisation,  and 
that  the  recognition  of  the  binding  force  of  such 
agreements  presupposes  the  existence  of  a  highly 
organised  public  opinion  against  their  violation, 
so  that  contract  depends  upon  society  more  than 
society  upon    contract.      It    is    therefore    quite v 
impossible  for  us  to  take  Hobbes's  account  of  the 
compact  by  which  savagery  is  ended  and  civilised 
life  begun  as  serious  historical   fact.     Yet  it  is 
possible    to    suspect    that    the   reaction   against 
theories  of  the  origin  of  government  in  contract 
may  perhaps  have  been  carried  too  far  even  on  the 
historical  side.     History  itself,  at  least,  gives  us 
reason  to  believe  that  many  a  famous  community 
79 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

has  sprung  from  combinations  of  '  broken  men/ 
relics,  in  a  period  of  general  disintegration,  from 
many  distinct  ruined  tribes  or  cities,  who  have 
somehow  been  thrown  together  and  entered  into 
a  new  alliance  among  themselves,  and  in  such 
cases  the  new  community  must  clearly  have 
rested  upon  the  voluntary  agreement  to  unite  in 
mutual  support.  But,  in  any  case,  the  substance 
of  Hobbes's  reasoned  plea  for  absolutism  is  quite 
independent  of  the  largely  mythical  form  in 
which  it  is  clothed  by  the  author.  However 
governments  originate,  it  is  at  least  true  that 
their  permanency  depends  upon  the  recognitipn 
by  governors  and  governed  alike  of  certain  general 
principles  denning  the  functions  of  the  governor 
and  the  obligations  of  the  governed,fotnd  such 
recognition  may  not  unsuitably  be  represented  to 
the  imagination  as  an  implicit  bargain./  These 
principles  Hobbes  and  the  seventeenth/  century 
publicists  in  general  call  by  a  name  borrowed 
from  the  Roman  lawyers,  who  in  their  turn  had 
borrowed  it  from  the  Stoic  philosophers,  the  ( laws_ 
of  nature/  the  curious  result  of  this  appeal  to  the 
terminology  of  the  Roman  jurists  being  that,  in 
effect,  the  theorists  of  the  '  social  contract ' 
contrive  to  apply  to  political  institutions  of  a  very 
un-Roman  character  the  doctrines  of  the  Roman 
80 


MAKING   OF   THE   LEVIATHAN 

law  of  corporations.  There  is,  of  course,  no 
inconsistency  between  the  phrase  '  laws  of  nature  ' 
and  Hobbes's  doctrine  that  a  law,  in  the  sense  of 
a  command  by  a  superior,  is  impossible  until  the 
creation  of  a  public  authority  to  give  the  com 
mand,  since  Hobbes  is  careful  to  explain  that 
'  lgws,,of  nature  \  are  not  commands,  but  '  rules 
of  reason/  true  universal  propositions  as  to  the 
conditions  upon  which  settled  wellbeing  is  obtain 
able.  They  are  laws  in  the  sense  in  which  we 
apply  the  name  to  the  principle  of  Excluded 
Middle  or  to  that  of  the  syllogism,  not  in  the 
sense  in  which  it  is  given  to  the  Statute  of 
Mortmain  or  the  British  North  America  Act: 
'  A  law  of  nature  (lex  natural-is),  is  a  precept,  or 
genecaLrule  found  out  by  reason,  by  which  a  man 
is  forbidden  to  do  that  which  is  destructive  of  his 
life,  or  taketh  away^the  means  of  preserving  thej 
same,  and  to  omit  that  by  which  he  thinketh  it 
may  best  be  jjreserved'  (Leviathan,  c.  xiv.). 
Hobbes's  employment  of  the  word  '  forbidden  '  in 
this  sentence  is,  of  course,  metaphorical.  His 
meaning  is  simply  that  SI'TU^  pyery  man  desires  to. 
live,  reflection  shows  us  that  it  would  be  irrational/ 
our  liyp.a  or  t^  fail  t 


It  is  in  this,  and  not  in  any  mere  idealistic  sense, 
that  we  have  to  understand  the  declaration,  in 
F  81 


•I 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

the  first  chapter  of  the  De  Corpore  Politico,  that 
the  law  of  nature  is  identical  with  reason.  It  is 
not  that  reason  is  thought  of  as  supplying  us 
with  ends  of  action :  the  ends  of  action  are  already 
given  by  the  fundamental  brute  passions  and 
appetites.  What  reason  does  is  to  indicate 
general  rules  as  to  the  means  by  which 
such  foregone  endsjaay  be  most  certainly 
obtained. 

Of  such  '  general  rules  found  out  by  reason/ 
there  are,  according  to  Hobbes,  a  considerable 
number,  but  all  are  deducible  from  a  single 
supreme  rule, '  that  every  man  ought  to  endeavour 
peace  as  far  as  he  has  hope  of  obtaining  it,  and 
where  he  cannot  obtain  it,  that  he  may  seek  and 
use  all  helps  and  advantages  of  war.  The  first 
branch  of  which  rule  containeth  the  first  and 
fundamental  law  of  nature,  which  is  to  seek  peace 
and  follow  it ;  the  second  the  sum  of  the  right  of 
nature,  which  is,  by  all  means  we  can  to  defend 
ourselves'  (Leviathan,  c.  xiv.).  (Of  course,  by 
saying  that  we  'ought'  to  seek  peace,  Hobbes 
means  no  more  than  that,  in  virtue  of  the  hazards 
and  dangers  of  the  '  war  of  all  against  all,'  it  is 
manifestly  to  our  advantage  to  do  so  where  we 
can.)  An  immediate  corollary,  which  figures  as 
the  second  law  of  nature,  is  that  each  of  us  should 

82 


MAKING  OF  THE  LEVIATHAN 

be  willing,  when  the  rest  are  equally  willing,  to 
abandon  the  general  claim  to  act  exactly  as  he 
thinks  fit,  so  far  as  the  renunciation  is  necessary 
for  peace ;  '  that  a  man  be  willing,  when  others 
are  so  too,  as  far  forth  as  for  peace  and  defence  of 
himself  he  shall  think  it  necessary,  to  lay  down 
this  right  to  all  things,  andjpe  contented^with  sfr 
much  liberty  against  other  men  as  he  would  allow^,, 
other  men  against  himself  (Ib.)  Briefly,  then, 
the  second  law  is  '  do  not  to  others  what  you  are  « 
not  prepared  to  allow  them  to  do  to  you/  a  precept 
which  Hobbes,  characteristically  enough,  confuses 
with  the  '  golden  rule  '  of  the  Gospel.  It  is  upon 
this  rule  that  the  whole  possibility  of  contract,  fc 
and,  consequently,  according  to  Hobbes,  of  political 
society,  depends.  For  what  J^he  rule  provides 
for  is  the  laying  aside  by  each  member  of  a  body 
of  men  of  some  part  of  his  original  right,  as 
described  in  the  first  of  Hobbes's  'rules  of 
reason/  to  act  exactly  as  he  thinks  fit.  Now 
rights  laid  aside  are  either  merely  renounced,  or, 
when  they  are  resigned^for  the  benefit  of  an 
expressly  designated  person  or  persons,  trans 
ferred  to  that  person  or  persons.  Such  trans- 
ference.being  a  voluntary  act,  is  necessarily 
7 interested,  since  thff  nhjfto.fi  of  every  vo1nnf.fl.rj 
frftt  iff  gome^good  to  myself.  The  contracting 


THOMAS  HOBBES 


parties,  then,  in  every^case,  ^Qt  each  with  a  view 
to  his  own  ultimate  advantage.  Also,  since  there 
are  certain  things  for  the  surrender  of  which  no 
man  can  receive  an  equivalent,  there  are  things 
which  cannot  be  made  the  subjects  of  contract, 
rights  which  cannot  be  transferred.  A  man  can- 
jp  not  e.g.  divest  himself  of  the  right  to  resist  an 
assault  upon  his  life,  or  an  attempt  to  wound  or 
imprison  him.  More  generally,  since  the  whole 
object  of  a  transference  of  rights  is  to  obtain 
an  increased  security  of  life  and  the  means  of 
enjoying  life,  no  act  or  word  of  mine  can  reason 
ably  be  interpreted  as  showing  an  intention  of 
divesting  myself  of  the  means  of  self-preserva 
tion.  These  considerations  will  meet  us  again 
as  furnishing  some  limits  even  to  the  power  of 
the  sovereign. 

Hobbes  now  proceeds  to  deduce  from  this 
second  law  a  third,,  which  is  the  immediate 
foundation  of  the  rest  of  his  social  theory.  When 
two  parties  make  a  bargain  for  their  mutual 
advantage,  it  frequently  happens  that  one  of 
them  is  called  upon  to  perform  his  part  of  the 
contract  first  and  to  trust  the  other  to  discharge 
his  part  at  some  future  time.  In  this  case  the 
contract  is  called,  from  the  point  of  view  of  the 
second  party,  &  covenant.  From  the  second  law 


MAKING  OF  THE  LEVIATHAN 

of  nature   we   can   then   deduce  a  third,  which 

'^^•^••••^ 

Hobbes  treats  as  the  foundation  of  all  moral, 
obligation.  '  thaL^men  perform  their  covenants 
made'  (Leviathan,  c.  xv.).  This  follows,  because 
if  I  break  my  agreement  with  you,  then,  since 
your  object  in  the  original  agreement  was  to 
secure  some  good  to  yourself,  and  my  failure  to 
perform  what  I  undertook  has  frustrated  that 
object,  you  have  no  longer  any  inducement  to 
fulfil  your  part  of  the  bargain.  Thus  the  whole 
purpose  of  making  covenants  has  been  defeated  ; 
'  covenants  are  in  vain,  and  but  empty  words, 
and,  the  right  of  all  men  to  all  things  remaining, 
we  are  still  in  the  condition  of  war'  (Ib.).  _0n 
this  law  of  the  sacredness  of  a  covenant  depends 
the  distinction  of  justice  from  injustice,  and,  in 
directly,  the  whole  of  social  morality,  since  '  the  p 
definition  of  injustice.^  no  other  than  the  not 
performance  of  covenant.  And  whatsoever  is  not 
unjust  _is  just.'  (Ib.  Note,  incidentally,  that 
Hobbes  thus,  like  Schopenhauer,  treats  wrong 
doing  as  a  concept  logically  prior  to  right-doing.) 
This  definition  explains  what  Hobbes  had  meant 
by  saying  that  in  *  a  state  of  nature '  there  can 
be  no^ injustice.  Injustice  is  breach  of  covenant, 
but  the  mutual  trust  upon  which  the  making  of 
covenants  depends,  is  only  possible  when  there 

85 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

is  a  coercive  power  which  can  affect  breaches  of 
covenant  with  penalties  severe  enough  to  make 
it  to  my  interest  to  abstain  from  them,  i.e.  under 
a  civil  government.  For  the  same  reason  it  is 
only  under  civil  government  that  there  can  4ae 
property.  It  is  a  natural  question  why,  if  the 
motive  for  loyalty  to  my  agreements  is  always 
some  prospect  of  advantage  to  myself,  I  should 
••  be  morally  bound  to  keep  them  in  cases  where 
treachery  promises  to  be  still  more  advantageous. 
The  fact  of  the  obligation  Hobbes  does  not  dis 
pute  ;  he  even  maintains  expressly  that  a  promise 
to  a  brigand  to  pay  a  certain  sum  on  condition 
of  being  released  is  binding  unless  declared  in 
valid  by  a  properly  constituted  court  of  law ;  but 
he  is  not  altogether  successful  in  the  reasoning 
by  which  he  supports  his  view.  Partly  he  replies 
that  a  promise-breaker  is  not  likely  to  gain  in 
the  long-run,  since  no  one  will  trust  him  after 
^  his  detection ;  partly  he  obscurely  hints  that  there  | 
L  may  be  a  final  judgment  of  God  to  be  reckoned 
with.  Apparently  this  suggestion  is  not  merely 
made  for  the  benefit  of  the  orthodox  reader  but 
represents  a  laudable  inconsistency  in  the  author's 
own  views,  a  belief  that  honesty  is  not  merely  the 
best  policy,  but  has  a  higher  sanctity  of  its  own 
which  Hobbes's  analysis  of  jnorality  fails  to 
86 


MAKING  OF  THE  LEVIATHAN 

account  for.  Perhaps  he  was  more  deeply  influ 
enced  than  he  knew  by  the  traditional  English 
hatred  of  a  lie,  as  something  inherently  base. 

JHobbes  now  enumerates  no  less  than  sixteen 
subsidiary   '  laws   of  nature/  that   is,   conditions 
without  which  peaceable  common  existence  would 
be  impossible.      The   general  character  of  the 
'  laws  '  is  negative  ;  they  are  prohibitions  of  varioi 
forms  of  behaviour  which   may  be  expected  1 
lead  to  a  breach  of  the  peace,  and  the  deductio] 
in  each  case,  takes  the-  form  of  an  appeal  to  sel 
interest.      E.g.  if  I   show  myself  revengeful,  c 
arrogant,  or  unwilling  to  refer  a  dispute  between 
myself  and  my  neighbour  to  a  disinterested  and 
impartial  arbitrator,  I  am  doing  what  lies  in  me 
to  prolong  the  '  state  of  war/  and  am  thus  losing 
the  increased  security  of  life  and  enjoyment  of 
its  good  things  which  peace  would  have  given 
me.      The  whole   body  of   the  nineteen  'laws/ 
Hobbes  says,  may  be  summed  up  in  the  simple 
formula   which    had   already   been  given   as   an 
equivalent  for  the  second  '  law  ;  :    '  To   leave  all 
men  unexcusable,  they  have  been  contracted  into 
one  easy  sum,  intelligible  even  to  the  meanest 
capacity,   and   that   is.   Do   not   that   to 


which  thou  wouldest  not  have   done  to  thyself; 
which  sheweth  him  that  he  has  no  more  to  do 

87 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

in  learning  the  laws  of  nature,  but  when,  weighing 
the  actions  of  other  men  with  his  own,  they 
seem  too  heavy,  to  put  them  into  the  other  part 
of  the  balance  and  his  own  into  their  place,  that 
his  own  passions  and  self-love  may  add  nothing 
to  the  weight;  and  then  there  is  none  of  these 
laws  of  nature  that  will  not  appear  unto  him  very 
reasonable '  (Leviathan,  c.  xv.). 

We  see,  then,  that  Hobbes's  'laws  of  nature,' 
looked  at  as  a  whole,  afford  a  fair  formulation  of 
the  fundamental  negative  condition  upon  which 
the  maintenance  of  social  order  depends  ;  no  man 
is  to  expect  more  from  his  neighbours  than  he  is 
willing  that  they  should  expect  from  him,  and 
no  man  is  to  interfere  with  the  doings  of 
his  neighbours  in  any  way  in  which  they  may 
not  equally  interfere  with  his.  The  competitors 
in  the  great  struggle  of  life  are  to  start  fair,  and 
to  'play  the  game.'  What  we  should  seek  in 
vain  in  any  of  Hobbes's  expositions  of  his  social 
doctrine  is  the  great  Hellenic  conception  of  the 
state  or  community  as  having  a  further  positive 
function,  a  duty  to  ennoble  the  lives  of  its 
members,  so  that  each  of  them  may,  if  he  will, 
climb  to  spiritual  heights  which  he  could  not 
have  scaled  alone.  Hobbes  can  hardly  be  said 
to  have  any  real  belief  in  social  institutions  as  the 
88 


/  J 

MAKING  OF   THE  LEVIATHAN 

instruments  and  bearers  of  progressive  civilisation, 
he  treats  them  as  merely  so  much  machinery  for 
the  preservation  of  a  status  quo.  He  has  mastered 
only  the  first  half  of  Aristotle's  famous  dictum 
that  'the  city  comes  into  being  that  men  may 
live,  but  continues  to  be  that  they  may  live 
well.' 

We  may  now  pass  at  once  to  a  demonstration 
of  the  necessity  of  the  organised  state  and  its 

^machinery.  The  ' laws  of_ nature '  are,  indeed,  in 
themselves  a  sufficient  _code  of  conduct,  and  if 
they  were  always  observed,  peaceful  social  existence 
would  be  guaranteed  _with  all  its  accompanying 

0  benefits.  But  in  the  '  state  of  nature '  we  can 
have  no  security  that  they  will  be  obeyed.  They 
'  oblige  iuforo  interno:  that  is  to  say,  they  bind< 
a  desire  they  should  take  place ;  but  in  foro 
externo,  that  is,  to  the  putting  them  in  act,  not 
always,'  since  a  man  who  persisted  in  keeping 
them  while  all  his  neighbours  broke  them,  would 
infallibly  lose  by  his  conduct,  and  it  is  impossible, 
on  Hobbes's  theory  of  human  nature,  that  a  man 
should  persist  in  doing  what  he  knows  to  be 
contrary  to  his  private  interest.  Thus  they  are, 
rightly  speaking^  not >  as  _yet  laws,  so  long  as  men 
remain  in  a  '  state  of  nature.'  For  a  law  means 
a  command  given  and  enforceable  by  a  definite 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

person.  '  These  dictates  of  rbason  men  use  to 
call  by  the  name  ofjiaws,  but  improperly;  for 
they  are  but  conclusions  or  theorems  concerning 
what  conduceth  to  the  conservation  and  defence 
,--  ,  of  themselves,  whereas  law  properly  is  the  word 
of  him  that  by  right  hath  command  over  others  ' 
(Leviathan,  c.  xv.).  What  is  needed,  then,  to 
secure  actual  obedience  to  them  is  that  they 
should  be  converted  into  commands  issued  by  an 
authority  which  has  rightful  claims  to  obedience, 
and  has  also  sufficient  force  at  its  disposal  to 
secure  obedience  by  the  infliction  of  such  penalties 
for  disobedience  as  may  make  it  always  to  a 
man's  own  advantage  to  obey.  What  is  needed 
is,  in  fact,  the  institution  of  a  ruler,  or  sovereign, 
and  with  the  creation  of  the  ruler  we  have  passed 
at  once  into  a  state  of  civil  society,  or  political 
subjection.  This  is  why,  with  Hobbes,  the 
creation  of  a  ruler  or  chief  magistrate  is  identical 
with  the  creation  of^sociefe  itself,  and  rebellion 
against  the  ruler  equivalent  to  the  dissolution  of 
the  social  bond  itself. 

Before  we  go  on  to  examine  the  way  in  which 
the  ruler  is  created,  there  are  two  points  to  which 
it  is  essential  to  call  attention  if  Hobbes  is  not  to 
be  greatly  misjudged.  In  spite  of  his  insistence 
upon  the  view  that  the  '  dictates  of  reason '  do  not 
90 


MAKING  OF  THE  LEVIATHAN 

become  actual  commands  until  there  is  some  one 
to  enforce  them,  Hobbes  js  not  justly  chargeable 
with  the  identification  of  the  moral  law  with  the 
caprices  of  an  autocrat.  The  validity  of  the  moral 
law,  though  not  its  character  as  '  law',  is  with  him 
anterior  to  the  establishment  of  the  ruler,  and 
depends  upon  what  he  takes  to  be  the  demon-  ^ 
strable  coincidence  of  morality  with  the  general 
interest.  What  the  ruler  is  needed  for  is  to  pro 
vide  the  individual  with  a  standing  adequate 
incentive  to  behave  morally,  and  Hobbes  is  at 
great  pains  to  urge  that  his  favourite  constitution, 
an  absolute  monarchy,  is  precisely  the  form  of 
society  in  which  the  ruler  is  least  likely  to  have 
any  personal  interest  independent  of  the  well- 
being  of  the  community,  and  may  therefore  be 
most  safely  trusted  to  see  that  his  '  laws '  embody 
nothing  but  the  conditions  necessary  for  peace 
and  security. 

And  again,  though  Hobbes's  argument  amounts 
to  a  defence  of  absolutism,  the  defence  is  through 
out  based  on  rationalistic  and,  consequently, 
democratic  grounds.  He  is  entirely  free  both 
from  the  superstition  of  a  '  divine  hereditary  right ' 
inherent  in  monarchs,  such  as  the  Stuarts  laid 
claim  to,  and  from  the  doctrine  that  mere  forcp^ 
itself  constitutes  right.  His  object  is  to  show  that 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

the  absolute  authority  of  the  sovereign  has  a 
foundation  in  right  by  tracing  it  back  to  its 
supposed  origin  in  a  voluntary  '  transference  of 
right '  on  the  part  of  the  subject,  a  transference 
made  in  the  interests  of  the  subject  himself,  and  so 
to  legitimate  absolutism  by  giving  it  a  utilitarian 
basis.  The  jure  divino  royalists  were  thus  com 
pletely  justified  in  their  instinctive  distrust  of 
Hobbes.  When  once  it  is  granted  that  absolute 
sovereignty  is  only  defensible  if  it  can  be  shown 
to  be  for  the  general  interest,  the  door  is  opened 
for  further  inquiry  whether  absolutism  really  is 
for  the  general  interest  or  not,  and,  if  it  can  be 
shown  that  it  is  not,  for  the  rejection  of  absolutism 
itself.  Thus  Hobbes's  theories  really  contain  the 
germs  of  the  constitutionalism  which  he  com 
bated.  To  declare  that  absolutism  requires  an 
utilitarian  justification  is  to  be  already  half-way 
on  the  road  to  revolution;  there  is  much  more 
community  of  spirit  between  Hobbes  and  Locke 
or  Sidney,  or  even  Rousseau,  than  between  Hobbes 
and  Filiner. 

The  immediate  object  of  Hobbes's  deduction  of 
the  rights  of  the  sovereign  is  closely  connected 
with  the  political  controversies  of  his  own  time. 
He  is  anxious  to  disprove  the  claims  made  by 
Parliament  against  the  British  Crown  to  be,  in 
92 


MAKING  OF  THE  LEVIATHAN 

a  special  sense,  the  representative  of  the  people 
and  of  popular  rights.  He  therefore  sets  himself 
to  argue  that,  in  every  society,  the  supreme 
executive  authority  is  already  itself  the  true 
representative  of  the  whole  community ;  the 
community,  consequently,  cannot  be  again  '  repre 
sented'  by  any  other  institution,  and  all  claims 
made  by  such  institutions  to  authority  co-ordinate 
with,  or  superior  to,  that  of  the  executive,  on  the 
plea  of  their  '  representative  '  character,  must  be 
nugatory.  To  effect  this  proof,  he  has  recourse 
to  the  technical  terms  of  the  Roman  law  of 
corporations  and  their  legal  representation.  He 
starts  with  the  legal  definition  of  a  person.  A 
person  means  any  being  whose  words  and  acts 
are  considered  in  law  as  issuing  either  from  him 
self  or  from  any  other  man  or  thing  to  whom  they 
are  attributed.  In  the  latter  case,  where  the 
words  and  acts  of  such  a  person  are  legally 
regarded  as  belonging  to  some  other  being  or 
beings,  whom  he  represents,  the  representer  is 
an  artificial  person  (e.g.  an  advocate,  speaking 
from  his  brief,  is  an  artificial  person,  who  repre 
sents  his  client ;  what  he  says  is  taken  in  law  as 
if  it  were  uttered  by,  and  committed,  not  the 
advocate  himself,  but  his  client).  When  the 
being  thus  represented  by  another  owns  .the  - 
93 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

words  and  acts  of  his  representative,  he  is  said 
to  authorise  them,  and  the  representative  speaks 
and  acts  with  authority,  so  that  an  act  done  by 
authority  always  means  an  act  'done  by  com 
mission  or  license  from  him  whose  right  it  is.' 
This  at  once  leads  to  the  conclusion  that,  by 
the  '  law  of  nature,'  any  being  who  has  '  author 
ised'  another  to  represent  him  is  bound  by  all 
engagements  entered  into  by  his  representative 
on  his  behalf,  so  far  as  they  come  within  the 
scope  of  the  authorisation,  exactly  as  if  they 
were  his  own  words  or  acts.  To  repudiate  them 
is  to  be  guilty  of  a  breach  of  the  law  that 
covenants  when  made  are  to  be  kept. 

This  point  being  granted,  it  only  remains  to 
establish  the  proposition  that  all  governments 
must  be  regarded  as  originating  in  a  commission 
bestowed  by  a  whole  community  upon  the  govern 
ment  to  '  represent '  it,  and  the  logical  defence  of 
absolutism  is  complete.  Accordingly  Hobbes  now_ 
proceeds  to  reason  as  follows.  An  &ggr_ega_te  .Q|JH- 
_dividual/meii  can  only  become  a  true  society  in  so 
far  as  it  exhibits  a  unity  of  will  and  purpose.  It  is 
this  unity  of  will  which  constitutes  the  multitude 
into  a  community.  But  there  is,  properly  speaking, 
no  such  thing  as  a  '  general '  will,  or  will  of  society 
at  large,  which  is  not  that  of  individuals.  Only 
94 


THE  LEVIATHAN 

by  a  legal  fiction  can  we  speak  of  anything  but 
individual  beings  as  endowed  with  will.     Conse 
quently,  the  unity  of  society  is  only  possible  by 
means  of  representation.    The  '  will '  of  the  society 
becomes  a  real  thing  when  the  original  aggregate 
agree  to  appoint  a  determinate  man,  or  body  of 
men,  their  representative,  i.e.  to  take  the  volitions 
of  that  man,  or  that  body  of  men,  as  '  authorised  ' 
by  every  individual  composing  the  aggregate. 
•    In  this  way,  and  only  in  this  way,  an  aggregate 
may,  by  legal  fiction,  become  one  person,  i.e.  a 
collective  subject  of  legal  rights  and  duties.     'A 
multitude  jpf  men  are  madeone  person  when  they 
are  by  one  man,  or  by  one  person,  represented  so 
that  it  be  done  with  the  consent  of  every  one 
of  that  multitucTe  in  particular.    For  it  is   the 
unity  of  the  Representer,  not  the  unity  of  the 
Represented,  that  maketh  the  person  one.     And 
it  is  the  Representer  that  beareth  the  person,  and 
but  one  person;  and  unity  cannot  otherwise  be 
understood  in  multitude.    And  because  the  multi 
tude  naturally  is  not  one  but  many,  they  cannot 
be  understood  for  one,  but  many,  authors  of  every 
thing  their  representative  saith  or  doth  in  their 
name,  every  man  giving  their  common  representer 
authority  from  himself  in  particular,  and  owning 
all  the  actions  the  representer  doth '  (Leviathan, 

* 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

c.  xvi.).  The  only  way,  then,  in  which  an  aggregate 
of  men  can  form  themselves  into  a  society  for 
mutual  defence  against  outsiders,  and  against  one 
another's  anti-social  tendencies,  is  by  unanimous 
agreement  to-  appoint  some  definite  man,  or 
number  of  men,  to  act  as  their  representative, 
whose  commands  each  of  the  aggregate  is  hence 
forth  to  regard  as  issuing  from  himself,  and  by 
whose  actions  each  henceforth  is  to  regard  himself 
as  bound,  exactly  as  though  they  had  been  per 
formed  by  himself.  In  this  way,  the  'laws  of 
nature/  the  conditions  of  peace  and  security,  be 
come  actually  operative,  since  by  making  such 
an  agreement,  the  represented  implicitly  authorise 
their  representer  to  employ  their  united  physical 
force,  as  though  it  were  his  own,  in  restraint  of 
all  disobedience  to  his  commands,  and  thus  create 
a  coercive  power  adequate  enough  to  give  every 
individual  personal  motives  to  obey. 

'The  only  way  to  erect  such  a  common  power 
.  .  .  is  to  confer  all  their  power  and  strength  upon 
one  man,  or  upon  one  assembly  of  men,  that  may 
reduce  all  their  wills,  by  plurality  of  voices,  unto 
one  will  ;  which  is  as  much  as  to  say,  to  appoint 
one  man,  or  assembly  of  men,  to  bear  their  person  ; 
and  every  one  to  own  and  acknowledge 


author  of  whatsoever  he  that  so  beareth 
96 


MAKING  OF  THE  LEVIATHAN 

their  person  shall  apt  nr  ng.n«f>f  f,r>  fre  acted  in  those 
things  which  concern  the  common  peace  apcl 
safety,  andjbherein  to  submit  their  wills  to  his 
wjlljind  their  judgments  to  his  judgment.  This 
is  more  than  consent  or  concord ;  it  is  a  real  unity 
of  them  all  in  one  and  the  same  person,  made  by 
covenant  of  every  man  with  every  man.,, .  .  ..JThis 
done,  the  multitude,  so  united  in  one  person,  is 
called  a  CommonweciWi.  .  .  .  This  is  the  genera 
tion  of  that  great  Leviathan,  or  rather,  to  speak 
more  reverently,  of  that  mortal  God,  to  which 
we  owe,  under  the  immortal  God,  our  peace  and 
defence.  For  by  this  authority,  given  him  by 
every  particular  man  in  the  Commonwealth,  he 
hath  the  use  of  so  much  power  and  strength 
conferred  on  him,  that  by  terror  thereof  he  is 
enabled  to  form  the  wills  of  them  all  to  peace 
at  home  and  mutual  aid  against  their  enemies 
abroad.  And  in  him  consisteth  the  essence  of  the 
Commonwealth,  which,  to  define  it,  is  one  person, 
of  whose  acts  a  great  multitude,  by  mutual 
covenants  one  with  another,  have  made  them 
selves  every  one  the  author,  to  the  end  that 
he  may  use  the  strength  and  means  of  them 
all  as  he  shall  think  expedient  for  their  peace 
and  common  defence.  And  he  that  carrieth  this 
person  is  called  Sovereign  and  said  to 
G  97 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

sovereign    power,    and    every    one    besides,    his 
subject'  (Leviathan,  c.  xvii.). 

One  or  two  points  in  this  deduction  call,  perhaps, 
for  special  remark.  (1)  It  should  be  clear  that,  in 
spite  of  his  absolutist  leanings,  what  Hobbes  is 
trying  to  express  by  the  aid  of  his  legal  fictions 
is  the  great  democratic  idea  of  self-government. 
The  coercive  powers  of  the  ruler  are  only  legiti 
mated  in  his  eyes  by  the  thought  that  they  give 
effect  to  what  is  at  heart  the  will  of  the  whole 
people  over  whom  he  rules ;  the  sovereign  is,  in 
effect^  tha. incarnation  of  the  national  will.  But 
as  his  philosophy  will  not  allow  him  to  admit  the 
reality  of  any  purpose  which  is  not  that  of  a  definite 
man,  he  has  to  conceive  of  this  national  spirit  and 
purpose  as  having  no  actual  existence  until  it  is 
embodied  in  a  representative  of  flesh  and  blood. 
The  nation  is  one  man,  with  a  will  j-nd  purpose  of 
its  own,  but  it  is  one  only  by  the  legal  fiction 
which  treats  the  acts  of  an  agent  or  representative 
as  if  they  were  those  of  that  which  he  represents. 
To  borrow  an  analogy  from  the  case  of  the 
individual,  the  soul  of  the  great  artificial  'body 
politic'  is  not  diffused  over  the  whole  organism, 
'all  in  every  part/  but  definitely  located  in  a 
central  organ,  or  brain.  This  is  why  Hobbes  is 
so  careful  to  insist  that  legitimate  sovereignty 

98 


-\THAN 
MAKING  OF  THE  LEYIA1. 

of  his 
must  be  based  on  an  express  or  tacit  consent  ^ 

every  member  of  the  subject  body,  and  also  why 
he  is  afterwards  at  great  pains  to  argue  that 
his  favourite  form  of  government,  the  absolute 
sovereignty  of  a  single  man,  is  just  the  one  in 
which,  from  the  nature  of  the  case,  the  ruler  is 
least  likely  to  have  any  private  interests  of  his  own 
distinct  from  those  of  the  community,  and,  in 
fact,  is  most  nearly  a  mere  mouthpiece  of  the 
national  will. 

(2)  With  Hobbes,  as  we  see,  the  creation  of  a 
commonwealth,  and  the  creation  of  a  central 
coercive  or  executive  power,  form  one  and  the 
same  act.  It  is  by  the_constituiiQn  of  an  execu 
tive  that  the  '  laws  of  nature^wjiich  bid  men  to 
seek  peace  and  ensue  it,  cease  to  be  amiable  but 
impracticable  ideals  an^Jbe^ojiia-OpQiative  realities. 
He  is  thus  the  author  of  the  doctrine,  revived 
in  the  nineteenth  century  by  Austin  and  his 
disciples,  that  sovereign  power  is  in  its  nature  one 
and  indivisible,  and  that  there  can  be  no  real 
distinction  between  the  different  functions  of 
government,  so  that  the  making  of  laws  may 
belong  to  one  set  of  persons,  the  enforcing  them 
by  penalties  to  a  second,  and  the  interpretation 
of  them  in  particular  cases  to  a  third.  It  is  on 
this  point  that  Hobbes's  political  theory  is  most 
99 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

s°Jfkingly  at  variance  with  those  of  his  best- 
known  successors.  When  Locke  formulated  the 
philosophy  of  the  Revolution  Whigs  in  his 
treatises  on  Civil  Government,  he  was  inevitably 
led,  in  the  attempt  to  justify  resistance  to  a  chief 
magistrate  who  violates  his  trust,  to  make  a  dis 
tinction  which  is  opposed  to  the  central  thought 
of  Hobbes.  With  Locke  the  fundamental  and 


*  gf>fl]*||]  fiompftftt  '  consists  simply  in  the 

determination  of  a  number  of  men  to  live  in  future 
under  a  known  and  common  law  of  action  instead 
of  being  guided  by  the  uncertain  and  fluctuating 
dictates  ofljjidiyidtuil  judgment,  i.e.  in  the  will  to 
establish  a  common  legislature.  The  appointment 
of  a  definite  set  of  persons  armed  with  power  to 
put  the  decisions  of  this  legislature  into  act  —  the 
creation  of  executive  officials  —  is  a  later  proceed 
ing,  and  the  chief  magistrate  thus  becomes  a  mere 
delegate  of  the  legislature,  a  trustee,  who  may 
lawfully  be  removed  whenever  he  transgresses  the 
limits  of  the  powers  delegated  to  him.  Locke  is 
thus  the  author  of  the  famous  doctrine  of  the 
'  division  of  powers  '  between  distinct  '  branches  ' 
of  government,  and  of  the  theory  of  the  import 
ance  of  'constitutional  checks,'  by  which  one 
'branch'  may  be  hindered  from  usurping  the 
functions  of  the  others. 

100 

\ 


MAKING  OF  THE  LEVIATHAN 

(3)  We  might  perhaps  add  that  in  virtue  of  his 
definition  of  the  ends  of  government  as  exhausted 
by  the  preservation  of  'peace  and  common  de 
fence,'  Hobbes  may  be  regarded  as  a  forerunner 
of  the  negative  laisser  alter  doctrine  of  the 
functions  of  the  state.  The  sovereign  is  there,  in 
fact,  to  remove  certain  standing  obstacles  to  the 
secure  prosecution  by  his  subjects  of  their  in 
dividual  aims,  to  keep  society  from  relapsing  into 
primitive  anarchy.  With  his  defective  theory  of 
volition,  Hobbes  can  naturally  find  no  place  for 
any  conception  of  the  state  as  an  organisation  for 
the  positive  promotion  among  its  members  of  the 
'  good  life '  or  '  civilisation '  or  '  progress/  or  what 
ever  else  we  may  please  to  call  that  ideal  of  life, 
by  which  the  rationally  free  man  is  distinguished 
from  the  barbarian.  The  very  existence  of  moral 
and  social  progress  is,  in  fact,  just  the  one  striking 
feature  of  historical  civilisation  which  his  account 
of  human  nature,  to  be  consistent  with  itself,  is 
bound  to  ignore. 


101 


CHAPTER  V 

THE  POWERS  OF  THE  SOVEREIGN 

THAT  the  legitimate  powers  of  a  sovereign  are 
absolute,  and^ that  all  resistance  to  his  autEorSy~ 
must  be  a'  'breach  of  covenant/  and  therefore 
unjust,  are  consequences  which  follow  directly 
jrom  Hnhhfig^  conception^pF  the  fundamental 
conditions^  social  ^existence.  The  sovereign  has, 
in  fact,  been  authorised  by  me,  if  I  am  a  member 
of  the  Commonwealth,  to  make  what  regulations 
he  thinks  fit  for  the  preservation  of  order  and 
peace,  and  to  use  the  whole  physical  force  of  the 
community  to  punish  or  prevent  violations  of 
those  regulations.  Refusal  to  obey,  or  resistance 
to  the  execution  of  the  sovereign's  command  is 
thus  a  distinct  breach  of  my  given  promise,  and 
against  the  '  law  of  nature,'  i.e.  the  rational  con 
sideration,  that  covenants  ought  to  be  kept,  i.e. 
that  the  making  of  them  is  useless  unless  they 
are  kept.  Hence  the  duty  of  unconditional 
obedience  on  the  part  of  the  subject.  But  there 
1 02 


±'  THE  SOVEREIGN 

is  nq_.  corresponding  duty  on  the  part  of  the 
sovereign.  He  has  been  expressly  authorised  to 
make  such  regulations  as  he  thinks  fit,  and,  .con 
sequently,  no  violation  of  compact  can  be  pleaded 
against  him,  no  matter  what ^commands  he  may 
Mak  .goad,  to  issue.  Hobbes  throws  this  latter 
part  of  his  argument,  which  aims  at  justifying 
the  Stuart  claim  of  irresponsibility  of  the  kings 
of  England  to  their  subjects,  into  a  curiously  arti-< 
ficial  form.  The  argument  by  which  the  sovereign 
is  set  up  is,  he  says,  one  between  each  individual 
member  of  a  crowd  and  every  other.  There 
has  been  no  agreement  between  the  whole  com 
munity  as  such,  on  the  one  part,  and  the  sovereign, 
on  the  other.  Before  the  creation  of  the  Levi 
athan,  in  fact,  the  community  has  no  corporate 
existence,  as  such,  and  the  sovereign  is,  as  yet,  no 
sovereign,  but  only  one  man,  or  a  number  of  men, 
among  others,  and  therefore  there  are  no  such 
parties  as  sovereign  and  public  to  bargain  with 
one  another.  Or  even  if  we  suppose  that  the 
person  finally  created  sovereign  had^pf^m^ed  his 
nomination  by  private  bargaining  with  individual 
members  of  the  crowd,  yet  when  once  he  has  been 
declared  sovereign  all  these  bargains  become  in 
valid,  since  he  now,  as  sovereign,  has  the  right  to 
say  what  agreements  shall  or  shall  not  be  con- 
103 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

sidered  binding.  Hence  no  act_of_  a__soyereign 
towards  any  of  his  subjects  can  be  unjust;  in  a 
commonwealth,  justice,  in  fact,  simply  means 
observing  the  rules  of  conduct  which  the  sovereign 
has  laid  down  (Leviathan,  c.  xviii.).  But  if  I  plead 
that  I  was  not  a  party  to  the  original  agreement 
of  every  man  with  every  man  to  accept  this  par 
ticular  sovereign,  and  to  acknowledge  his  acts  as 
if  they  were  my  own,  then  he  is  not  my  sovereign 
at  all,  and  I  am  no  member  of  the  society  which, 
as  such,  is  created  by  his  elevation.  Towards  him 
and  them  I  am  still  in  '  the  state  of  nature/  and 
may  without  injustice  be  treated  as  an  enemy,  and 
subject  to  all  that  is  incidental  to  the  'war  of  all 
against  all/ 

It  follows  that  a  sovereign,  once  instituted,  can 
.in  no  case  be  guilty  of  an  injustice  towards  any  of 
his  subjects.  And  JEEobbes  bids  us  take  note  that 
in  the  psalm  whicife  according  to  the  notions  of 
the  seventeenth  century,  expresses  David's  peni 
tence  for  adultery  and  murder,  no  acknowledgment 
is  made  that  the  author  had  done  a  wrong  to 
Uriah  in  first  corrupting  his  wife  and  then  com 
passing  his  death;  it  is  for  sin  against  God 
I  that  the  Psalmist  entreats  forgiveness,  not  for 
wrong  done  to  man.  So,  Hobbes  concludes,  it  is 
the  teaching  of  Scripture,  as  well  as  of  reason, 
104 


POWERS  OF  THE  SOVEREIGN 

that  the  ruler  can  never  be  unjust  to  his  subject, 
and  therefore  never  lawfully  accused,  judged,  or 
condemned  by  those  who  have  themselves  agreed 
to  take  his  orders  as  the  measure  of  just  and 
unjust.  Still,  it  is  admitted,  a  ruler  may  abuse 
his  power,  as  David  did,  and  if  this  is  not  injustice 
to  the  subject,  it  is  at  least  iniquity  for  which 
the  ruler  is  amenable  to  the  judgment  of  God. 
'  Though  the  action  be  against  the  law  of  nature, 
as  being  contrary  to  equity  (as  was  the  killing  of 
Uriah  by  David),  yet  it  was  not  an  injury  to  Uriah, 
but  to  God.  Not  to  Uriah,  because  the  right  to 
do  what  he  pleased  was  given  him  by  Uriah  him 
self;  and  yet  to  God  because  David  was  God's 
subject,  and  prohibited  all  iniquity  by  the  law  of 
nature..  Which  distinction  David  himself,  when 
ne  repented  the  fact,  evidently  confirmed,  saying, 
To  Thee  only  have  I  sinned  (Leviathan,  c.  xxi .).' 
As  in  a  former  case,  this  suggestion  of  a  divine 
judgment  to  whft^even  the  irresponsible  sovereign 
is  amenable,  leaves  us  in  a  perplexing  uncertainty 
how  far  it  is  a  concession  to  the  weaknesses  of 
orthodox  readers,  or  how  far  it  may  represent  a 
genuine  feeling  on  the  writer's  part  that  there  is, 
after  all,  a  moral  authority  more  ancient  and 
august  than  the  various  leviathans  men  have 
made  for  themselves. 

105 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

It  must  not  of  course  be  supposed  that  it  is 
only  a  monarch  who  can  be  absolute.  Hobbes  is 
careful  to  point  out  that  it  follows  from  his  theory 
of  the  'social  compact'  that  every  government, 
when  once  duly  established,  whatever  its  form 
may  be,  is  clothed  with  the  same  absolute  au 
thority  over  its  subjects.  Indeed,  it  is  in  the  case 
of  a  '  democracy/  i.e.  a  state  in  which  the  whole 
assembly  of  citizens  is  itself  the  sovereign  body, 
that  he  thinks  the  fact  of  absolute  authority  most 
patent.  'When  an  assembly  of  men  is  made 
sovereign,  then  no  man  imagineth  any  such 
covenant  to  have  past  in  the  institution,  for  no 
man  is  so  dull  as  to  say,  for  example,  the  people  of 
Rome  made  a  covenant  with  the  Romans  to  hold 
the  sovereignty  on  such  and  such  conditions, 
which  not  performed,  the  Romans  might  lawfully 
depose  the  Roman  people.  That  men  see  not 
the  reason  to  be  alike  in  a  monarchy  and  in 
a  popular  government  proceedeth  from  the 
ambition  of  some,  that  are  kinder  to  the  govern 
ment  of  an  assembly,  whereof  they  may  hope  to 
participate  than  of  monarchy,  which  they  despair 
to  enjoy.'  (Leviathan,  c.  xviii.)  Hobbes  is,  how 
ever,  of  opinion  that  of  all  forms  of  government 
monarchy  best  answers  the  purpose  for  which 
sovereignty  is  instituted,  and  that  for  several 
1 06 


POWERS  OF  THE  SOVEREIGN 

reasons:    (1)  A    monarch's    private    interest    is 
more  intimately  bound  up  with  the  interests  of 
his  subjects  than  can  be  the  case  with  the  private 
interests  of  the  members  of  a  sovereign  assembly. 
'  The  riches,   power,  and   honour  of  a  monarch 
arise  only  from  the  riches,  strength,  and  reputation 
of  his  subjects.  .  .  .  Whereas  in  a  Democracy  or 
Aristocracy,   the    public  prosperity   confers    not 
so  much  to  the  private  fortune  of  one  that  is 
corrupt   as   doth   many  times    a    perfidious   ad 
vice,    a    treacherous    action,    civil    war'    (76.,   c. 
xix.) — a   sentence   upon    which    the    history   of 
the   relations   of  the  restored   Stuarts  with   the 
Court  of  France  surely  affords  an  entertaining 
commentary.     (2)  A  monarch  is  freer  to  receive 
advice  from  all  quarters,  and  to  keep  that  advice 
secret,    than    an    assembly.      (3)    Whereas    the 
resolutions  of  a  monarch  are  subject  only  to  the 
\inconstancy    of    human    nature,    those    of    an 
assembly  are  exposed  to   a  further  inconstancy 
arising  from  disagreement  between  its  members. 
Monarchy  thus  offers  the  maximum  of  security 
for    'continuity'    of    policy.       (4)    A    monarch 
'cannot   disagree   with  himself  out   of  envy   or 
interest,  but  an  assembly  may,  and  that  to  such 
a  height   as   may  produce   a  civil   war'   (76.,  c. 
xix.). 

107 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

Against  these  advantages  of  monarchy  may  be 
pleaded  two  disadvantages,  (1)  the  ill  effects 
produced  by  the  influence  of  flatterers  and 
favourites  with  the  monarch,  and  (2)  the  disorders 
which  arise  when  the  monarchy  descends  to  an 
infant  or  an  imbecile.  These,  however,  are  dis 
counted  by  considering  (1)  that  flatterers  and 
favourites,  in  the  form  of  interested  demagogues, 
are  as  common  in  popular  as  in  monarchical 
government;  and  under  the  former  have  more 
power  to  do  harm  and  less  to  do  good  than  under 
the  latter.  '  For  to  accuse  requires  less  eloquence 
(such  is  man's  nature)  than  to  excuse ;  and  con- 
<^mnation,than  absolution,  more  resembles  justice' 
eviathan,  c.xix.);  and  that  the  powers  of  an  infant 
imbecile  monarch  can  always  be  placed  in  the 
,nds  of  a  qualified  body  of  regents,  and  therefore 
iy  disturbances  that  arise  must  be  attributed 
not  to  the  inherent  defects  of  monarchical 
government,  but  to  '  the  ambition  of  subjects,  and 
ignorance  ot  their  duty'  (76.).  As  we  have 
already  seen,  Hobbes's  conception  of  human 
nature  and  the  ends  of  action  precludes  his 
reckoning  with  what  a  more  idealistic  philosophy 
would  probably  regard  as  the  chief  objection  to 
despotism,  even  when  it  is  both  benevolent  and 
capable,  viz.  the  conviction  that  freedom  and  self- 
108 


POWERS  OE  THE  SOVEREIGN 


nature  absolute       o  ^  ^ 

vindicating  for  the       g  ,  d  b    the  Puritan 

powers  which  had  been  challenged    j  ^ 

jtfSRSZ  go--* 
monarch  is  m  <Acts    of 


the  monarc  ^  <A 

modern  phrase,  m    accord 
Parliament.'    Parliament  is  merdy          7  ^  ^ 
together  by  the  Anarch  to   Jvisg  ^  ^ 

state  of  the  kmgdom  and  th  Q{  ^ 

taken  for  the  common  P*-  ^  ^ 

elected  Parliament  "**>£*    \s    entirely  un 
•representative  of    tte     >    P  completel; 

founded.     The    people  are  ^  al       y      mQnMcl 
.^resented'  ^  ^  sove^gn  ^ 

and    consequently  ^^^  it  enjo; 
again.    What  powers  Parham 

^    -    a   ^S  o  1  People,'^ 
the  real  <  represent  atw  e  reject  lt, 

therefore  free  J°  ^fj'^thout  consulti 
to  promulgate  laws  of  h^n^ 

it    as  he    thinks   best  ,(1  _ 


THOMAS  HOBBES 


take  charge 

* 


the 

Control  of 
(3) 


im''Sted 
controversy 


to 

-ecessary  to  the 
demand  of  the 

*«  militia  was  an 
momrch,  again,  has  the  s 
at  hs  own  discretion   a  r  1 

by  Hobbes  with^fere 
ship.mon        ,  " 

from  hisUtLn        t 
all  the  rules  of  iusl!       °  authori 
deciding  ajl  Jj  a>bce.e°wn»te,  of  - 

which 

natural,  or  con. 
aX  since, 

against  aaother' 
opposition  to    he 
the  Star 


from 


°f 


opions 

COndUpcingn: 


r,0 


<to  ^ 
there- 


POWERS  OF  THE  SOVEREIGN 

fore,  that  it  is  for  him,  and  for  him  alone,  to 
decide  'on  what  occasions,  how  far,  and  what 
men  are  to  be  trusted  withal  in  speaking  to 
multitudes  of  people,  and  who  shall  examine  the 
doctrines  of  all  books  before  -they  be  published. 
For  the  actions  of  men  proceed  from  their 
opinions,  and  in  the  well  governing  of  men's 
opinions  consisteth  the  well  governing  of  men's 
actions  in  order  to  their  peace  and  concord' 
(Leviathan,  c.  xviii.).  Of  the  bearing  of  this  con 
clusion  upon  Hobbes's  views  of  the  ecclesiastical 
supremacy  of  the  sovereign  I  shall  have  some 
thing  to  say  in  the  next  chapter. 

It  must  be  observed  that  the  highly  doctrin 
aire  character  of  this  defence  of  the  Royalists' 
position  at  once  lays  it  open  to  a  damaging  attack 
which  Hobbes  does  nothing  to  meet.  He  has 
proved  conclusively,  if  you  grant  the  truth  of  his 
peculiar  view  of  human  nature,  that '  peace  and 
concord'  are  only  attainable  in  political  society. 
He  has  also  shown  that  in  every  political  society 
there  must  be  somewhere  a  centre  of  authority 
endowed  with  plenatyjfewers,  and  only  restrained 
in  the  exercise  of  them  by  the  consideration  that 
governmental  authority,  pushed  beyond  a  certain 
point,  will  provoke  rebellion  and  so  defeat  its 
own  ends.  What  he  has  not  proved,  but  is  con- 
iii 


THOMAS   HOBBES 

tent  simply  to  assume,  is  that,  as  a  matter  of 
historical  fact,  this  plenitude  of  power  is,  under 
the  constitution  of  England,  reposed  in  the  person 
of  the  king,  or  in  other  words,  that  the  govern 
ment  of  England  is  really  a  monarchy  in  his 
sense  of  the  term.  Now  this  was  precisely  what 
the  Parliamentarian  statesmen  denied.  Accord 
ing  to  them,  the  powers  of  the  English  Crown  were, 
in  point  of  fact,  and  had  always  been,  circum 
scribed  by  a  superior  authority,  which  is  described 
e.g.  in  the  Petition  of  Right,  as  '  the  laws  and 
statutes  of  the  realm,' '  the  laws  and  customs  of 
this  realm,'  and  they  had,  as  we  know,  sound 
historical  reasons  to  urge  in  support  of  this  view 
,  of  the  case.  <  As  Hobbes  never  takes  issue  on  the 
historical  question,  his  leading  opponents  would 
have  been  perfectly  justified  in  calling  his  argu 
ment,  as  applied  to  the  proceedings  of  the  Parlia 
mentarians,  an  elaborate  ignoratio  elenchi.'  The 
question  at  issue  between  Charles  i.  and  Hampden 
or  Pym  was  not  whether  the  ultimate  seat  of 
authority  in  England  is  'absolute'  or  not,  but 
where  that  seat  of  authority  lies.  Hobbes's 
evasion  of  the  real  question  throws  a  flood  of  light 
upon  the  fundamental  weakness  of  the  theory 
which  treats  government  as  legitimated  by  '  con 
tract.'  Such  a  hard  and  fast  theory  is  bound  to 

112 


POWERS  OF  THE  SOVEREIGN 

be,  at  some  point  or  other,  discrepant  with  the 
actual  facts  of  the  historical  situation.  A  consti 
tution  is  not  a  thing  which  is  made  once  for  all 
by  the  wisdom  of  .a  .particular  set  of  persons ;  it 
is  something  which  grows  up  gradually  under  all 
sorts  of  perceptible  and  imperceptible  infJaasnces. 
At  any  given  time,  the  various  formulae  by  which 
it  is  described  by  those  who  live  under  it  are 
sure  to  be  only  imperfectly  consistent  with 
one  another.  Nay,  further,  since  the  formulae  for 
the  most  part  are  things  devised  to  fit  a  past  state 
of  affairs,  which  continue  to  be  repeated  long  after 
the  situation  they  describe  has  been  profoundly 
modified  in  fact,  they  are  almost  certain  to  be 
largely  false  when  accepted  as  an  account  of  the 
stage  of  development  actually  reached,  long 
before  they  lose  their  inherited  prestige.  And  of 
development  and  progress  as  great  social  facts, 
Hobbes,  as  we  saw,  has  as  good  as  no  conception. 

From  his  examination  of  the  powers  of  the 
sovereign,  Hobbes  advances  to  a  consideration  of 
the  liberties  of  the  subject.  One  might  be 

**^0./..r.. ......  V.1  --*,<~W.^.^  —    .Jl^.  O 

tempted  to  think  that  the  latter  must  be  non 
existent  in  such  a  scheme  as  his.  But  there  are 
certain  inevitable  limits  even  to  the  most  unre 
stricted  absolutism,  and  there  are  others  which 
suggest  themselves  as  soon  as  absolutism  itself  is 
H  113 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

treated  as  only  defensible  on  a  utilitarian  basis. 
What  these  limits  are,  according  to  Hobbes,  is 
explained  in  chapter  xxi.  of  the  Leviathan. ....  The 
'liberty  of  the  subject'  is  simply  that  part  of  the 
supposed  original  'right  of  every  man  to  every 
thing  '  of  which  he  cannot  possibly  have  divested 
himself,  or  of  which  he  cannot  be  supposed  to 
have  divested  himself  without  defeating  his  pur 
pose  in  entering  into  the  'social  compact' — viz., 
I  the  preservation j)f  himself.  He  is  free  then  (1)  to 
refuse,  even  when  commanded  by  the  sovereign, 
to  kill  or  maim  himself,  or  to  submit  without 
resistance  to  those  who  are  charged  to  kill  or 
maim  him ;  (2)  to  refuse  to  confess  a  crime,  except 
upon  previous  promise  of  pardon ;  (3)  to  refuse  to 
execute  an  order  to  kill  another  man,  and  more 
generally  to  decline  any  dangerous  or  dishonour 
able  office  by  executing  which  he  imperils  that 
very  self-preservation  for  the  sake  of  which  he 
has  entered  into  social  life.  On  this  ground 
Hobbes  justifies  the  refusal  of  'men  of  feminine 
courage '  (like  himself)  to  do  personal  service  as 
soldiers,  provided  they  are  ready  to  furnish  a 
sufficient  substitute.  Even  a  band  of  rebels,  he 
holds,  may  without  injustice  refuse  to  capitulate 
except  on  a  promise  of  pardon.  To  these  elemen 
tary  liberties  we  subsequently  find  added  com- 
114' 


POWERS  OF  THE  SOVEREIGN 

plete    liberty   of   conscience,   so  far    as   private 
thoughts  are  concerned.     Thought  is  absolutely 
free,  si T^ply  because  it. is  impossible  to  subject  it; 
the  expression  of  thought  in  words,  as  we  have 
seen,  is  not  free  at  all,  it  being  for  the  sovereign 
to  decide  what   thoughts  may  be  made  public 
without  danger  to  the  peace.     It  has  only  to  Jje 
added  that  the  authority  of  a  sovereign,  of  nmrrBft, 
only  lasts  so  long  as  he  is  able  to   ensure  the 
general  safety,  for  no  covenant  can  deprive  a  man 
ot'Jiis  right  to  protect  himself  when  he  has  no 
other  protector.     Political  allegiance  is  therefore  I v 
terminated,  the  life  of  the  Leviathan  extinguished,! 
when  a  monarch  is  captured  in  war  and  purchases 
his  personal  liberty  by  submission  to  the  con-l 
queror,  or  when  he  voluntarily  releases  his  sub-l 
jects  from  their  obedience,  and  so  declares  that  he  j 
no  longer    embodies    the  public  will    for    self-  V 
protection. 


CHAPTER    VI 

CHUKCH   AND   STATE 

SINCE  it  has  been  already  declared  that  the 
sovereign,  in  the  interests  of  the  general  peace, 
has  the  sole  right  to  determine  what  opinions  may 
be  safely  taught  in  the  commonwealth,  it  follows 
at  once  that  Hobbes  can  allow  of  no  division 
between  a  civil  and  a  spiritual  power.  In  fact  he 
holds,  as  a  man  of  the  seventeenth  century  not 
unreasonably  might,  that  the  most  potent  of  all 
sources  of  anarchy  and  civil  disorder  is  precisely 
the  claim  of  the  clergy  of  various  churches  to 
possess  an  inherent  right,  not  depending  on  any 
grant  from  the  political  authority,  to  declare  what 
religious  doctrines  shall  be  taught  and  what  form 
of  church  discipline  permitted,  and  to  depose  or 
rebel  against  civil  rulers  who  refuse  to  submit  to 
their  dictation  on  these  points.  Writing,  as  he 
did,  in  the  seventeenth  century,  Hobbes  found  it 
necessary  to  plead  the  cause  of  Erastianism  not 
only  on  grounds  of  reason,  but  by  the  aid  of  an 
116 


CHURCH  AND  STATE 

appeal  to  Scripture,  and  the  consequence  is  that 
nearly  a  half  of  Leviathan  is  taken  up  by  the 
ecclesiastical  controversy  in  which  he  has  to 
oppose  at  once  the  Romanist,  the  Scotch  Cove 
nanter,  and  the  ordinary  Anglican  High  Church-  ^ 
man.  It  is  impossible  in  a  short  sketch  like  the 
present  to  do  more  than  indicate  the  general 
character  of  the  singular  result  at  which  he 
arrives.  The  key  to  his  whole  position  must  be 
sought  in  his  pithy  aphorism  that  religion  is  not-'  v 
philosophy,  but  law.  That  is,  the  sovereign 
authorises  the  preaching  of  certain  doctrines  and 
prohibits  others,  not  because  the  former  are  scien 
tifically  true,  and  the  latter  false  (in  fact,  we  saw 
long  ago  that  all  doctrines  about  God  lie  outside 
the  limits  of  human  knowledge),  but  because  the 
...  former  are  conducive  to  peace,  and  the  latter  to 
discord.  And  our  profession  of  faith  in  the 
authorised  religion  is  to  be  understood  not  as  a 
declaration  of  our  philosophical  belief,  but  as  a 
declaration  of  our  submission  to  the  rightful  poli-  j 
tical  authority  of  the  sovereign.  Hobbes  has  then 
to  meet  the  objection  that,  on  his  view,  our  duty  to 
the  sovereign  must,  whenever  the  sovereign  is  an 
'  infidel/  lead  us  into  disobedience  to  God.  The 
'infidel'  sovereign  commands  us  to  practise  a 
'  false '  religion,  God  commands  us,  in  his  Word, 
117 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

to  embrace  the  '  true.'  Are  we  then  to  obey  man 
rather  than  God,  and  must  the  martyrs  who  died 
for  the  faith  be  accounted  criminals?  Hobbes's 
reply  is,  in  principle,  that  we  have  to  learn  what 
is  the  '  true '  religion  from  the  '  canonical '  Scrip 
tures,  and  that  a  writing  depends  for  its  '  canon 
ical  '  character  upon  its  authorisation  as  such  by 
the  sovereign,  who  also,  in  virtue  of  his  general 
right  to  prohibit  dangerous  teaching,  is  the  final 
court  of  appeal  as  to  the  interpretation  of  '  Scrip 
ture.'  It  must,  therefore,  be  vain  to  plead  our 
interpretations  of  some  work  which  we  regard  as 
'inspired'  in  justification  of  our  refusal  to  submit 
to  the  sovereign.  As  for  the  martyrs  of  history, 
no  man  can  be  a  '  martyr,'  or  witness  for  the  truth 
of  a  revelation  from  God,  except  its  .immediate 
recipient.  All  that  any  other  martyr  can  testify 
to  is  his  belief  in  the  veracity  of  the  person  who 
claims  to  have  received  the  revelation.  To  reject 
his  witness  is  thus  not  to  reject  his  commands  of 
God,  but  merely  to  reject  the  claims  of  a  certain 
person  to  have  had  communications  with  God. 
Now  the  only  way  in  which  a  man  can  prove  his 
divine  commission  is  by  the  performance  of 
miracles,  and  since  miracles  have  ceased,  no  one 
can  now  establish  his  claims  to  be  believed  as  a 
messenger  of  God  except  indirectly  by  the  agree- 
118 


CHURCH  AND  STATE 

ment  of  his  teaching  with  that  of  Christ  and  the 
apostles.  But  Christ  and  the  apostles  taught, 
both  by  precept  and  by  example,  the  duty  of 
submission  to  civil  authorities.  Hence  no  man 
can  claim  their  authority  in  favour  of  disobedience 
to  the  sovereign.  In  the  purely  hypothetical  case 
of  a  man  receiving  to-day  a  direct  command  from 
God  to  disobey  his  sovereign,  he  must,  no  doubt, 
be  prepared  to  obey  God,  who  can  make  it  his 
highest  interest  to  do  so,  rather  than  the  sove 
reign  ;  but  since  he  is  unable  to  prove  his  divine 
commission  by  miracles,  he  has  no  ground  for 
complaint  if  the  sovereign  refuses  to  believe  in 
it  and  punishes  him  as  an  offender. 

To  make  this  doctrine  more  palatable  to  his 
readers,  Hobbes  combines  it  with  an  elaborate 
scriptural  exegesis  of  his  own,  in  the  develop 
ment  of  which  he  rivals  or  outdoes  his  orthodox 
antagonists  in  profusion  of  biblical  quotations 
and  ingenuity  of  interpretation,  not  infrequently 
throwing  out  remarkable  anticipations  of  more 
modern  criticism,  f  The  fundamental  proposition 
of  the  whole  scheme  is  that  the  'kingdom  of 
God,'  spoken  of  in  Scripture,  is  not  an  ecclesi 
astical  system,  but  a  civil  government  in  which 
God,  as  represented  by  a  visible  human  lieutenant, 
reigns  as  civil  sovereign.  This  kingdom  was  first 
119 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

instituted  when  Moses  was  directly  installed  by 
God  as  His  representative  in  the  government  of 
the  Jews,  but  suspended  when  that  people  revolted 
from  their  lawful  rulers,  the  successors  of  Moses, 
and  set  up  the  kingdom  of  Saul.  The  mission 
of  Jesus  was  to  announce  its  restoration,  not  in 
his  lifetime,  but  in  an  age  yet  to  come,  when  the 
righteous  are  to  rise  from  the  dead  and  be  reigned 
over  personally  by  Jesus,  as  God's  representative, 
in  Palestine.  Hence  the  only  condition  imposed 
from  the  first  as  necessary  for  entrance  into  the 
Church  was  the  acknowledgment  of  the  belief  that 
Jesus  is  the  '  Messiah/  i.e.  the  destined  monarch 
of  the  coming  '  Kingdom  of  God.'  All  that  a 
Christian  is  obliged  to,  therefore,  as  a  condition 
of  salvation  is  the  belief  that  at  some  future  time 
Jesus  will  reappear  on  earth  as  a  civil  sovereign, 
and  the  intention  of  then  obeying  his  authority ;  I 
in  the  meanwhile  the  Christian  is  bound,  by  the 
express  language  of  Scripture  itself,  to  complete 
submission  to  the  existing  civil  power.  As  for 
the  '  Church/  which  sometimes  claims  to  be  the 
1  Kingdom  of  God '  announced  by  Jesus,  and  con 
sequently  to  have  a  first  lien,  so  to  say,  on  the 
obedience  of  Christians,  Hobbes  gives  us  a  choice 
of  alternatives.  'If  it  be  one  person,  it  is  the 
same  thing  with  a  commonwealth  of  Christians, 
1 20 


CHURCH  AND  STATE 

called  a  commonwealth  because  it  consisteth  of 
men  united  in  one  person,  their  sovereign,  and  a 
church  because  it  consisteth  in  Christian  men 
united  in  one  Christian  sovereign.  But  if  the 
church  be  not  one  person,  then  it  hath  no 
authority  at  all ;  it  can  neither  command,  nor  do 
any  action  at  all  ...  nor  has  any  will,  reason, 
nor  voice,  for  all  these  qualities  are  personal.' 
(Leviathan,  c.  xxxiii.)  It  is  then  argued  at  length 
that  the  only  commission  given  by  Christ  to  his 
apostles,  and  by  them  to  their  successors,  was  to 
teach  and  persuade,  and  the  only  weapon  with 
which  they  were  armed  against  the  recalcitrant, 
the  power  of  excommunication,  i.e.  the  threat  of 
exclusion  from  the  future  'Kingdom  of  God.' 
Such  power  as  the  clergy  now  exercise  in  Christian 
countries,  then,  is  derived  from,  and  dependent 
on,  the  political  sovereign,  who  is  the  single 
fountain  at  once  of  temporal  and  'spiritual' 
authority.  They  are,  in  fact,  so  far  as  concerns 
their  social  status,  a  body  of  civil  servants,  and 
nothing  more,  and  Hobbes  declares  that  whereas 
the  king  of  England,  as  responsible  to  no  tribunal 
on  earth,  may  rightly  claim  to  rule  Dei  gratia,  a 
bishop  holds  his  see  'by  the  grace  of  God  and 
the  king's  permission.' 

The  fourth  and  last  division  of  Leviathan  is 
121 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

devoted  to  an  unsparing  attack,  conducted  chiefly 
with  an  eye  to  Bellarrnine's  arguments  for  Papal 
supremacy,  upon  '  the  kingdom  of  darkness/  that 
is,  the  church  organised  as  a  society  independent 
of  the  authorisation  of  the  civil  power,  and  claim 
ing  an  independent 'spiritual' jurisdiction  to  be 
enforced  at  its  peril  by  the  '  secular  arm '  through 
the  medium  of  temporal  disabilities  and  penalties. 
The  origin  of  this  '  kingdom  of  darkness '  is  sought 
in  the  ambition  of  the  Roman  clergy,  which  led 
them  first  to  accept  support  and  grants  of  power 
from  the  Christian  Roman  Emperors,  and  finally, 
in  the  general  decay  of  the  imperial  system,  to 
usurp  the  place  of  their  original  protectors.  '  If 
a  man,'  says  Hobbes,  in  one  of  his  most  famous 
epigrams,  '  considers  the  original  of  this  great 
ecclesiastical  dominion,  he  will  easily  perceive 
that  the  Papacy  is  no  other  than  the  ghost  of  the 
deceased  Roman  Empire  sitting  crowned  upon 
the  grave  thereof.  For  so  did  the  Papacy  start 
up  on  a  sudden  out  of  the  ruins  of  that  heathen 
power '  (Leviathan,  c.  xlvii.).  The  ghost,  Hobbes 
adds,  has  partly  been  exorcised  in  England,  first 
by  the  Tudor  sovereigns  who  overthrew  the  power 
of  the  Pope,  then  by  the  Presbyterians  of  the 
Long  Parliament  who  put  down  the  Bishops,  and 
finally  (we  must  remember  that  this  sentence, 
122 


CHURCH  AND  STATE 

which  does  not  appear  in  the  modified  Latin  text 
of  1669,  was  written  in  1651),  by  the  Indepen 
dents,  who  destroyed  the  domination  of  Presby- 
terianism,  'and  so  we  are  reduced  to  the  inde 
pendency  of  the  primitive  Christians,  to  follow 
Paul  or  Cephas  or  Apollos,  every  man  as  he 
liketh  best,  which,  if  it  be  without  contention  .  .  . 
is  perhaps  the  best'  (/&.).  But>  ne  a(Ws>  tne 
exorcism  will  never  be  complete  until  a  bold 
ruler  takes  in  hand  the  universities,  the  chief 
sources  hitherto  of  high  ecclesiastical  pretensions, 
and  compels  them  to  instruct  their  students  in 
the  true  rudiments  of  political  science,  and  the 
true  grounds  of  political  submission.  That  is, 
said  his  critics,  until  the  Leviathan  is  officially 
made  the  sole  text-book  of  political  science. 


123 


CONCLUSION 

> 

THE  true  measure  of  Hobbes's  greatness  as  a 
philosopher  was  hardly  recognised  either  by  his 
own  contemporaries  in  England  or  by  their  suc 
cessors  of  the  eighteenth  century.  The  innumer 
able  attacks  of  the  orthodox  upon  his  theories,  on 
the  ground  of  their  alleged  irreligious  and  im 
moral  tendency,  are  mostly  of  an  ephemeral  kind, 
but  the  attitude  of  Locke  and  Berkeley,  who  had 
capacity  enough  to  understand  him,  if  they  had 
cared  to  do  so,  and  who  would  have  found  his 
nominalism  at  least  entirely  to  their  taste  is  more 
significant.  Locke  never  mentions  his  name  at 
all  throughout  the  Essay,  and  when  accused  by 
Stillingfleet  of  arriving  at  results  similar  to  those 
of  Hobbes,  retorts  with  a  sarcasm  upon  the  good 
Bishop's  familiarity  with  a  'suspected'  author. 
Berkeley  mentions  him  once,  in  his  Alcipkron, 
along  with  Spinoza  and  Vanini,  as  a  typical  atheist. 
Though  Warburton,  with  his  usual  love  for  a 
paradox,  prided  himself  on  having  been  the  first 
person  to  discover  the  real  strength  of  Hobbes's 
124 


CONCLUSION 

position,  real  appreciation  of  his  merits  in  Eng 
land  begins  with  the  utilitarians  of  the  early 
nineteenth  century,  Austin,  Grote,  and  Moles- 
worth,  to  the  last  of  whom  we  owe  the  only 
approach  as  yet  made  to  a  complete  edition  of 
Hobbes's  works.  Down  to  their  time  Hobbes's 
chief  influence  on  English  thought  lay  in  the 
stimulus  his  ethical  theories  afforded  to  a  pro- 
founder  moral  analysis  and  a  deeper  study  of 
human  nature  on  the  part  of  antagonists  who 
sought  to  vindicate  the  originality  of  disinter 
ested  action  and  to  base  morality  upon  grounds 
independent  of  positive  law.  The  ethical  work  of 
Cudworth,  of  Shaftesbury,  of  Cumberland,  of 
Butler  is  throughout  inspired  by  the  felt  need 
to  meet  and  overcome  a  conception  of  human 
nature  which  goes  back,  in  the  end,  to  the 
philosopher  of  Mahnesbury.  On  the  Continent 
the  direct  influence  of  Hobbes  made  itself  more 
immediately  and  more  permanently  felt.  Within 
the  philosopher's  own  lifetime  Spinoza  had 
adopted,  as  the  basis  of  the  theory  of  government 
given  in  his  unfinished  Tractatus  Politicus,  a 
view  of  '  natural  right '  and  the  '  social  compact/ 
which  is,  in  all  fundamentals,  identical  with  that 
of  Hobbes,  whose  influence  is  also  visibly  traceable 
in  the  argument  for  the  freedom  of  philosophy 
125 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

from  theological  restraints  set  forth  in  the  famoi  • 
Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus.  Leibniz,  too,  in 
his  youthful  recoil  from  scholasticism  was  power 
fully  attracted  by  Hobbes's  clear-cut  logical 
nominalism  and  outspoken  materialism,  nor  did 
he  cease  to  express  his  admiration  for  the  English 
man's  genius  after  he  had  finally  arrived  at  his 
own  mature  doctrine  of  spiritual  realism.  It  has 
been  shown  that  throughout  the  eighteenth  cen 
tury,  down  to  the  time  of  Kant,  Hobbes  continued 
to  be  an  object  of  philosophic  interest  in  Ger 
many.  But  the  detailed  facts  as  to  his  influence 
at  home  and  abroad  belong  to  the  general  history 
of  modern  thought,  and  necessarily  fall  outside 
the  limits  of  a  brief  sketch  like  the  present. 


126 


BOOKS   USEFUL   TO   THE   STUDENT 
OF   HOBBES 

Editions  of  Works  : — 

The  Works  of  Thomas  Hobbes  of  Malmesbury.  Edited 
by  Sir  W.  Moles  worth.  16  vols.  (English  Works, 
11  vols  ;  Latin  Works,  5  vols.)  London,  John  Bohn, 
1839-1845. 

Leviathan.  Eeprints — (1)  In  Morley's  (now  Eoutledge's) 
Universal  Library;  vol.  xxi.  of  the  original  series. 
(2)  In  the  Cambridge  English  Classics,  1904.  (Cam 
bridge  University  Press.) 

The  Metaphysical  System  of  Hobbes,  as  contained  in  twelve 
chapters  from  his  '  Elements  of  Philosophy  Concerning 
Body,'  and  in  briefer  extracts  from  his  'Human  Nature ' 
and  'Leviathan,3  selected  by  Mary  Whitton  Calkins. 
Chicago,  Open  Court  Publishing  Co.  London,  Kegan 
Paul,  Trench,  Triibner  and  Co.,  1906. 

Monographs : — 

Hobbes,  by  Prof.  J.  Groom  Kobertson,  in  Blackwood's 
Philosophical  Classics.  Blackwood  and  Sons,  1886. 

Hobbes,  by  Prof.  F.  Tonnies,  in  Frohmann's  Classiker 
der  Philosophic,  No.  2.  Stuttgart,  1896. 

Hobbes,  by  Sir  Leslie  Stephen,  in  English  Men  of  Letters 
Series.  Macmillan  and  Co.,  1904. 

General  works  on  the  history  of  modern  thought : — 
History  of  Modern  Philosophy,   by  Prof.   H.   Hoffding. 
English  Translation.    Macmillan.    2  vols.    1900.    (For 
Hobbes  in  particular  see  vol.  i.  p.  259-291.) 
127 


THOMAS  HOBBES 

Principles  of  Political  Obligation,  by  T.  H.  Green.  (For 
Hobbes  in  particular  see  §§  42-50.)  Originally  pub 
lished  in  vol.  ii.  of  Works  of  Thomas  Hill  Green. 
Longmans,  Green  and  Co.,  1886  ;  since  reprinted  as  a 
separate  volume. 

The  Philosophical  Theory  of  the  State.  Bernard  Bosanquet. 
Macmillan  and  Co.,  1899. 

Outlines  of  the  History  of  Ethics.  Henry  Sidgwick.  Mac 
millan  and  Co. 


Printed  by  T.  and  A.  CONSTABLE,  Printers  to  His  Majeaty 
at  the  Edinburgh  University  Press 


/r 


vf 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY 


B  Taylor,  Alfred  Edward 

1247  Thomas  Hobbes 

T38 
cop.  2