Skip to main content

Full text of "Truth and reality; an introduction to the theory of knowledge"

See other formats


LIBRARY 

UNIVERSITY  Of 
CALIFORNIA 

SAN  D1«GO 


THE  LIBRARY 

OF 

THE  UNIVERSITY 
OF  CALIFORNIA 

LOS  ANGELES 

PROFESSOR  JOHN  ELOF  BOODIN 

MEMORIAL  PHILOSOPHY 

COLLECTION 


TRUTH   AND    REALITY 


o,  q«,  i  ar,  i 


THE  MACMILLAN  COMPANY 

NEW  YORK  •    BOSTON   •    CHICAGO 
SAN   FRANCISCO 

MACMILLAN  &  CO.,  LIMITED 

LONDON  •    BOMBAY  •    CALCUTTA 
MELBOURNE 

THE  MACMILLAN  CO.  OF  CANADA,  LTD. 

TORONTO 


TRUTH  AND  REALITY 

AN  INTRODUCTION  TO  THE 
THEORY  OF  KNOWLEDGE 


BY 

JOHN    ELOF    BOODIN 

PROFESSOR  OF  PHILOSOPHY,   UNIVERSITY   OF   KANSAS 


ff  0tfc 

THE    MACMILLAN   COMPANY 
1911 

All  rights  reserved 


COPYRIGHT,  1911, 
BY  THE  MACMILLAN  COMPANY. 


Set  up  and  electrotyped.    Published  October,  1911. 


Notfaonfi  $rr*8 

J.  8.  Gushing  Co.  —  Berwick  <fc  Smith  Co. 
Norwood,  Mass.,  U.S.A. 


MY   FRIEND   AND   TEACHER 

WILLIAM  JAMES 

NOT  THE   LATE    BUT  THE   EVER   LIVING 

AND   INSPIRING  GENIUS   OF 

AMERICAN   PHILOSOPHY 

THIS    BOOK 
IS   AFFECTIONATELY   DEDICATED 


PREFACE 

IT  is  my  hope  that  this  volume  may  serve  a  pur- 
pose as  an  introduction  to  the  theory  of  knowledge. 
While  we  have  pretentious  works  covering  the  field  of 
logic  and  epistemology,  we  are  not  so  well  supplied  with 
books  giving  a  general  survey  of  the  main  problems  in- 
volved in  the  investigation  of  truth.  The  time  seems 
peculiarly  ripe  for  such  an  effort.  In  the  bewildering 
amount  of  discussion  and  misunderstanding  to  which  the 
pragmatic  movement  has  led,  there  is  need  for  fresh  em- 
phasis of  the  main  issues.  There  is  also  need  for  building 
out  the  pragmatic  theory  hi  neglected  directions.  In  a 
small  way,  this  book  tries  to  serve  both  purposes. 

This  book  is  intended  to  be  used  in  connection  with  a 
course  in  elementary  logic  or  as  an  introduction  or  sequel 
to  it.  It  is  hoped  that  its  human  interest  will  also  make 
it  available  for  the  general  philosophic  reader  and  as  an 
introduction  to  philosophy.  To  the  cultured  public,  not 
technically  trained  in  philosophy,  the  first  and  the  last 
chapters  may  be  of  special  interest. 

My  relation  to  the  pragmatic  movement  will  be  clear 
enough  in  the  course  of  the  text.  It  may  be  of  interest 
that  the  larger  part  of  Chapter  XVII,  "The  Reality  of 
Religious  Ideals,"  was  given  as  a  lecture  at  Harvard  in 
1899,  practically  before  the  movement  had  started.  This 
direction  of  my  thought  was  in  part  due  to  the  influence  of 
Fichte  and  Herrmann's  Religionsphilosophie,  in  part  to 

vii 


viii  Preface 

my  personal  relations  to  William  James.  My  going  on 
with  the  work  in  the  last  few  years  is  altogether  due  to 
the  clarifying  influence  of  the  pragmatic  movement 

I  may  say  here  that  this  volume  will  be  followed  shortly 
by  another  on  metaphysics  entitled  A  Realistic  Universe, 
where  some  problems  suggested  in  this  book  will  be  dealt 
with  more  fully. 

I  am  under  obligation  to  the  following  journals  for 
permission  to  use  in  whole  or  part  material  which  has 
appeared  during  the  last  few  years.  Chapters  I,  IX, 
and  XIV  have  been  revised  from  the  Monist ;  Chapters 
II,  XI  (Truth  and  Meaning),  and  XII  from  the  Psycho- 
logical Review ;  Chapters  VII  and  VIII  (printed  as  the 
Nature  of  Truth  and  Discussion)  from  the  Philosophical 
Review ;  Chapters  X  and  XV  (published  as  Truth  and  its 
Object)  in  the  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology,  and  Sci- 
entific Methods ;  and  Chapter  XVII  from  the  Harvard 
Theological  Review. 

To  my  friends  and  colleagues,  Professor  S.  L.  Whitcomb 
and  Professor  E.  C.  Wilm,  I  am  indebted  for  reading  the 
proof,  and  for  many  valuable  suggestions. 


TABLE   OF   CONTENTS 

PART   I.     TRUTH   AND   MENTAL  CONSTITUTION 

CHAPTER  PACK 

I.     PHILOSOPHIC  TOLERANCE 3 

*II.     MIND  AS  INSTINCT 15 

III.  THE  CATEGORIES  OF  INTELLIGENCE     ....  43 

PART  II.  THE  NATURE  OF  TRUTH 

IV.  THE  TRUTH  PROCESS 67 

V.    THE  MORPHOLOGY  OF  TRUTH 86 

VI.    THE  CONTENT  OF  TRUTH 104 

VII.    THE  POSTULATES  OF  TRUTH 123 

VIII.    THE  POSTULATES  OF  TRUTH  CONTINUED      .        .        .146 

PART   III.     THE  CRITERION   OF   TRUTH 

IX.    FROM  PROTAGORAS  TO  WILLIAM  JAMES       .        .        .165 
X.    WHAT  PRAGMATISM  is  AND  is  NOT      .        .        .        .186 

XI.    MEANING  AND  VALIDITY 200 

XII.    TRUTH  AND  AGREEMENT 214 

XIII.  HUMAN  NATURE  AND  TRUTH 230 

PART   IV.     TRUTH   AND   ITS   OBJECT 

XIV.  PRAGMATIC  REALISM 251 

XV.    THE  OBJECT  AND  ITS  CONTEXTS 269 

XVI.    METAPHYSICS  —  THE  OVERLAPPING  PROBLEMS      .        .  291 

XVII.    THE  REALITY  OF  RELIGIOUS  IDEALS    ....  307 


jx 


PART  I 
TRUTH  AND  MENTAL  CONSTITUTION 


TRUTH   AND   REALITY 

CHAPTER   I.     INTRODUCTORY 

PHILOSOPHIC  TOLERANCE 

TO-DAY  as  I  sit  before  the  warm  grate  fire  with  the 
snowflakes  falling  outside,  I  feel  in  a  peculiarly  dreamy 
and  charitable  mood  towards  all  mankind,  especially 
philosophers.  Perhaps  I  have  what  Dooley  calls  the 
Carnegie  feeling.  At  any  rate  there  jar  upon  me  more 
than  usually  the  petty  nagging  and  jostling  and  rushing  to 
the  patent  office  in  the  philosophic  camp,  as  though  one 
small  head  could  carry  all  of  truth,  or  as  though  one  ex- 
pression of  truth,  however  comprehensive,  could  be  more 
than  a  passing  phase  of  experience  as  a  whole.  Consider- 
ing the  variety  of  human  nature  as  a  result  of  evolution, 
why  should  it  not  require  an  indefinite  number  of  systems 
to  express  human  nature  in  the  various  stages  of  its  de- 
velopment and  in  its  various  moods  ?  And  why  are  they 
not  all  true,  in  so  far  as  they  are  really  genuine  and  really 
express  human  nature  then  and  there  ?  Philosophers, 
above  all  people,  need  open-mindedness  and  a  sense  of 
humor.  Dogmatism  has  erected  the  stakes  and  the  gib- 
bet for  those  who  have  ventured  on  any  new  path,  while 
philosophy  must  always  breathe  the  air  of  freedom,  and 
has  always  proved  wiser  in  its  hero-worship  than  in  its 
persecution. 

3 


4  Truth  and  Reality 

This  brings  to  my  mind  an  occasion  in  one  of  the 
temples  of  Boston,  made  more  venerable  in  its  associations 
since  then.  It  was  a  discussion  of  educational  ideals  at  a 
meeting  of  a  brilliant  group  of  educators.  It  was  a  Babel 
of  many  tongues,  one  saying  :  It  is  this  way  ;  another :  It 
is  this;  one  saying:  Come  to  us,  we  have  the  latest;  an- 
other :  Come  to  us,  we  have  the  most  venerable ;  another 
one :  Come  to  us,  we  have  the  best  equipped  bazaar  of 
learning.  I  remember  President  Eliot  rising  at  the  close 
of  the  discussion,  and  in  his  dignified  simplicity  gleaning 
in  unadorned  eloquence  the  wisdom  of  the  day.  I  do  not 
remember  his  exact  words,  but  the  import  of  them  was 
something  like  this :  "  Education  is  at  present  in  its  ex- 
perimental stage  ;  and  in  the  meantime  it  is  best  that  each 
experiment  should  be  carried  out  with  the  greatest  possible 
consistency  under  the  best  conditions.  Harvard  has  stood 
for  a  system  of  free  election  in  its  college  course.  It  is 
well  that  a  system  of  required  work,  under  the  best  condi- 
tions, should  be  tried  somewhere,  at  Princeton  perhaps. 
Thus  future  generations  shall  be  wiser  for  our  experi- 
ments." It  struck  us  all  as  so  eminently  sane. 

Why  is  this  not  true,  to  an  even  greater  extent,  of  phil- 
osophy, the  science  of  the  meaning  of  it  all  ?  Why  should 
we  not  welcome  and  encourage  different  experiments  ?  Is 
not  philosophy,  and  must  it  not  always  be,  in  the  experi- 
mental stage?  One  of  the  few  fragments  which  have 
survived  from  the  brilliant  author  of  the  homo  mensura 
tenet  is :  "  In  respect  to  the  gods,  I  am  unable  to  know 
either  that  they  are  or  that  they  are  not,  for  there  are 
many  obstacles  to  such  knowledge,  above  all  the  obscurity 
of  the  matter  and  the  life  of  man  in  that  it  is  so  short." 
Why  should  not  this  brevity  of  life  and  the  complex  and 


Philosophic  Tolerance  5 

changing  character  of  our  world  teach  us  modesty  in  the 
ultimate  matters,  where  our  little  lifetimes  and  limited 
points  of  view  must  be  supplemented  by  other  lifetimes 
and  other  points  of  view,  and  where  the  checkered  mosaic 
of  truth  never  can  be  completed?  Truth  is  at  best  ex- 
perimental, and  nothing  can  be  more  fatal  than  stopping 
the  experiment.  The  most  that  will  be  said  of  any  of  us 
in  the  ages  to  come  is :  Yes,  he  saw  a  phase  of  the  problem  ; 
or  he  proved  suggestive  in  the  infancy  of  the  science. 

I,  for  one,  though  I  have  elsewhere  urged  a  Weltan- 
schauung of  absolute  time  and  realistic  pluralism,  want  to 
see  the  experiment  of  absolute  idealism  carried  out  with 
the  best  psychological  and  methodological  advantages, 
and  I  confess,  rabid  realist  that  I  am,  that  in  some  moods, 
in  which  my  passion  for  permanence  and  unity  asserts 
itself,  I  take  comfort  in  absolute  idealism,  or  at  least  like 
to  play  with  it.  There  is  a  certain  intellectual  coziness 
about  absolute  idealism  for  which  I  sometimes  long.  I 
want  to  close  the  accounts  and  find  how  things  stand,  or 
at  least  feel  sure  that  somebody  knows  and  that  no  evil 
can  befall  my  ideals.  But  again,  in  other  and  with  me 
more  prevailing  moods,  this  esthetic  craving  gives  way  to 
the  respect  for  facts  as  they  seem,  to  the  longing  for  action 
and  risk;  and  I  sometimes  revel,  in  imagination  at  least, 
in  the  daring  and  courage  of  helping  to  make  an  unknown 
future,  in  which  my  plans  and  I  myself  may  prove  unfit. 
A  fair  field,  I  say,  and  no  favors,  not  even  for  my  own  pet 
theories.  There  are  other  moods,  too ;  and  only  God 
knows  which  is  the  truest  in  the  end.  Ideals  may  prove 
truer  than  facts. 

We  are  told  of  the  Chinese  that  he  has  several  religions, 
a  different  religion  for  different  functions  of  his  life.  As 


6  Truth  and  Reality 

a  public  official  and  statesman  he  is  a  Confucian,  this  being 
a  religion  of  ideals  for  public  life.  Again,  Buddhism  sup- 
plies the  need  for  ritual,  and  furnishes  a  larger  religious 
setting ;  while  Taoism,  with  its  forms  of  magic,  satisfies  the 
more  primitive  folklore  side  of  Chinese  nature.  Besides 
these  there  are  various  local  cults.  The  state  recognizes 
the  place  these  various  religions  have  in  Chinese  life  by 
supporting  them.  This  condition  of  things  causes  no  end 
of  trouble  to  the  Western  census  taker,  and  is  very  difficult 
for  us  sectarian  Occidentals  to  understand.  But  why  should 
we  insist  so  persistently  on  fitting  human  nature  into  one 
arbitrary  mold  for  the  sake  of  conventional  consistency  ? 
Why  should  we  not  have  recourse  to  different  forms  of 
religion  and  different  systems  of  philosophy,  different 
universes  of  appreciation,  according  to  the  varying  moods 
and  needs  of  the  soul  ?  Why  should  not  institutions,  which 
after  all  are  our  creations,  be  made  to  serve  us,  instead 
of  our  being  enslaved  by  them  ? 

Here  I  see  the  poetic  sanity  of  Plato,  which  has  troubled 
his  stupid  and  stereotyped  commentators  so  much.  The 
secret  of  the  difficulty  of  unifying  Plato,  over  which  so 
many  have  stumbled,  is  that  Plato's  philosophy  varies  with 
his  poetic  moods.  He,  as  no  other  philosopher,  coins  his 
own  soul ;  and  therefore  he  has  continued  to  speak  to  the 
soul  of  man  as  no  other  philosopher.  Each  dialogue  is  a 
Weltanschauung  by  itself.  Most  moods  seem  to  fit  the 
overshadowing,  large-hearted,  and  sane  personality  of 
Socrates;  but  in  other,  more  abstract  moods,  the  cold 
personality  of  Parmenides  or  Zeno  seems  more  fitting. 
We  have  not  Plato,  but  a  mosaic  of  the  rich  life  of  Plato. 
Why  should  not  every  sincere  man  express  his  life  in  a 
philosophy  that  seems  reasonable  to  him  at  the  time,  fits 


Philosophic  Tolerance  7 

experience  now  ?  It  is  easy  enough  for  the  man  who  deals 
in  mere  verbiage  to  manipulate  continually  the  same  iden- 
tical counters,  but  not  so  with  the  man  who  expresses  him- 
self. Thus  not  only  man,  but  the  different  moments  of 
man,  become  the  measure  of  all  things ;  and  the  Sophists, 
had  they  been  shrewd,  might  have  pointed  to  the  plastic 
nature  of  Plato  as  the  best  illustration  of  their  theory. 
Agreement  and  sameness  are  practical  necessities  for  the 
sake  of  common  action,  but  outside  the  elementary  qualifi- 
cations for  social  life  they  are  the  bane  of  progress. 

In  art  and  poetry  conventional  limitations  have  been  less 
effective  and  made  it  less  difficult  for  men  to  be  sincere 
with  themselves.  We  do  not  demand  rigid  consistency 
here.  We  are  disappointed  at  mere  repetition.  We  look 
for  a  different  mood  of  the  soul  in  every  new  work  of  the 
artist.  Here  human  nature  has  been  able  to  find  a  more 
varied  and  genuine  expression  for  its  complex  and  varying 
tendencies,  and  we  who  enjoy  the  art  find  here  a  varied 
supplement  for  our  varying  inner  attitudes.  Here  it  is  not 
a  question  of  either  or ;  there  is  no  need  here  of  finding 
a  common  denominator  of  different  types,  though  silly 
would-be  art  lovers  will  insist  on  nauseating  one  with  such 
questions  as :  What  is  your  favorite  painting  ?  your  favorite 
poem  ?  Poor  one-horse  souls.  In  the  realm  of  poetry  and 
art  we  have  a  right  to  have  our  whole  nature  ministered 
unto,  to  live  in  an  infinite  number  of  universes.  In  one 
mood  we  want  lyric  sweetness,  dreamy  romance,  Shelley 
and  Keats ;  in  other  moods  we  crave  for  the  searching  of 
tragedy,  for  something  that  will  appeal  to  the  deeper  self 
within  us,  and  so  we  ask  for  the  Antigone  and  Hamlet 
and  Othello.  Again  we  want  something  that  appeals  to 
the  heroic,  that  satisfies  the  boy  within  us,  —  and  he  is 


8  Truth  and  Reality 

always  there,  even  in  the  oldest  of  us,  —  so  we  take  up 
Homer.  What  is  the  use  of  taking  a  vote  on  the  world's 
greatest  poem  ?  The  greatest  for  me  is  that  which 
expresses  my  soul  most  perfectly  at  the  time.  Why 
should  I  not  enthrone  each  one  to  an  exclusive  place  in 
my  soul  according  to  my  needs,  as  the  ancient  Hindu 
enthroned  Indra  and  Agni  and  Varuna  in  turn  ?  There  is 
no  poetic  Absolute  unless  it  be  the  freedom  of  enjoying 
the  varying  expressions  according  to  the  varying  moods. 

What  is  true  in  poetry  is  equally  true  of  art  in  the 
narrower  sense.  Why  should  my  admiration  for  the 
Sistine  Madonna  prevent  me  from  enjoying  other  Ma- 
donnas of  Raphael,  different  moods  of  his  soul?  And 
why  should  my  love  for  Raphael  prevent  me  from  loving 
Millet  and  Corot  ?  Why  should  I  try  to  find  a  common 
denominator  for  a  Madonna  and  a  Sunset  ?  My  soul 
needs  them  both;  and  my  love  for  one  does  not  fill  the 
place  of  the  other,  any  more  than  my  love  for  Beethoven's 
symphonies  fills  the  place  of  Schubert's  songs  and  Bizet's 
Carmen.  To  be  sectarian  here  is  to  have  no  music  in 
one's  soul  and  to  be  fit  for  all  the  villainous  things  of 
which  Shakespeare  speaks. 

And  why  should  a  man's  soul  be  crowded  into  one 
system  of  philosophy  ?  The  ultimate  realities  with  which 
metaphysics  deals  are  no  less  plastic  in  the  hands  of  the 
potter  than  the  realities  of  art.  In  either  case  the  soul  is 
endeavoring  to  create  an  objective  counterpart  to  its 
tendencies  or  needs,  to  mirror  itself,  become  conscious  of 
itself,  and  so  to  create  anew  its  meaning  through  the 
expression  of  itself.  Philosophy,  like  poetry  and  art, 
when  it  is  genuine,  is  only  the  expression  of  a  mood  of  the 
soul,  and  it  is  not  always  for  the  artist  to  tell  what  mood 


Philosophic  Tolerance  9 

is  most  significant  Let  each  one,  then,  in  the  moment 
when  he  feels  the  impulse  to  create,  "from  his  separate 
star  draw  the  thing  as  he  sees  it,"  not  only  once,  but  again 
and  again,  as  he  feels  the  impulse  to  express  himself. 
Let  the  soul  create  its  belief-worlds  as  its  own  needs 
demand,  wrapping  its  belief-mantle  around  itself  to  make 
itself  cozy  in  the  world,  whether  to  lie  down  to  pleasant 
dreams  or  to  face  a  sea  of  trouble.  In  the  realm  of  truth, 
as  well  as  art,  man  must  be  the  measure,  however  finite 
and  passing  the  measure  may  be.  All  sincere  expression, 
therefore,  is  worth  while.  History  will  see  to  it  that  the 
fittest  survives.  At  least,  he  who  has  expressed  himself 
genuinely  has  become  repaid  by  the  insight  gained  in  his 
own  expressive  act  If  human  nature  in  his  case  is  rich 
and  deep,  as  well  as  sincere,  the  expression  becomes 
significant  not  only  for  him,  but  for  others  as  well,  a 
creation  of  new  social  values.  The  expression  of  human 
nature,  whether  it  is  a  measure  of  the  universe  or  not,  is 
always  a  measure  of  the  individual  soul  that  expresses 
itself.  The  reason  that  philosophy  has  exercised  so  small 
an  influence  upon  the  world,  compared  to  poetry,  art  and 
religion,  is  that  it  has  often  been  a  matter  of  verbiage,  with 
no  real  soul  back  of  it  Philosophic  meaning,  then,  like 
artistic  and  poetic,  is  a  mosaic  of  points  of  view,  of  belief- 
worlds,  rather  than  cut  out  of  whole  cloth  or  according  to 
one  pattern.  Whether  we  will  so  or  no,  our  moods  and  our 
lives  are  phases  merely  of  the  whole  process  of  reality,  and 
our  belief-worlds  are  phases  of  the  total  meaning.  At  best 
the  objective  counterpart  of  our  inner  attitudes  is  a  very 
fragmentary  expression  of  what  we  feel  and  mean.  Hence 
it  is  right  that  philosophy  should  have  its  Plato  as  poetry 
has  its  Shakespeare;  and  philosophy  needs  its  Walt  Whit- 


io  Truth  and  Reality 

man,  too,  to  reduce  it  to  what  is  elemental  and  make  it  sure 
of  its  sincerity.  "  Make  thyself  new  mansions,  oh,  my 
soul,"  must  be  the  motto  of  philosophy.  Let  the  architec- 
ture be  Greek  or  Gothic,  or  both,  as  the  soul  may  require. 
The  history  of  philosophy  is  a  picture  gallery  in  which  we 
can  study  not  only  the  history  of  thought,  but  the  history 
of  ourselves,  and  through  sympathy  with  the  past  become 
conscious  of  our  own  meaning  in  our  various  moods. 

To-day,  therefore,  I  feel  that  I  want  to  be  Chinese  in 
my  homage  to  philosophy  as  I  already  am  in  poetry  and 
art.  I  like  to  visit  sometimes,  in  the  company  of  my  friend 
Royce,  a  beautiful  Greek  temple  built  according  to  Plato's 
Idea  of  the  Good.  It  is  wonderfully  complete  and  satisfy- 
ing, carried  out  after  the  plan  of  one  master  artist  accord- 
ing to  perfect  mathematical  models,  frescoed  in  an  infinitely 
varied  pattern,  in  which  the  past,  present  and  future  are 
set  in  wonderful  mosaic  through  the  immortal  artist's  cun- 
ning. And  withal  the  soul  is  filled  with  such  sweet  har- 
mony as  to  forget  for  the  time  being  its  limitations  and  its 
longings.  You  can  only  gaze  in  rapture  and  wonder  at 
the  beauty  of  it  all.  So  impressed  was  I  that  I  turned  to 
my  friend  and  asked :  What  can  I  do  ?  He  replied  with 
a  smile  at  my  impatience :  Only  enjoy  the  eternal  beauty 
of  that  which  is.  And  it  was  wonderful  for  a  time  to 
dream  there,  while  I  could  keep  quiet  and  until  my  old 
restlessness  returned.  But  I  fancy  I  shall  sometime  steal 
in  again  for  another  quiet  hour,  to  see  Hegel  gazing  at 
his  chart  of  logical  categories,  Augustine  in  mystic  devo- 
tion, and  the  transfigured  countenance  of  Plato. 

But  sometimes  I  like  to  worship  in  another  temple,  very 
unlike  the  one  just  mentioned,  bare  and  simple  in  the  ex- 
treme. It  is  the  temple  of  Democritus  and  Priestley  and 


Philosophic  Tolerance  n 

other  stern  and  heroic  souls.  A  temple  did  I  say  ?  Yes, 
for  its  devotees  were  filled  with  a  tremendous  reverence 
and  enthusiasm.  Yet  no  ornaments  were  there,  nor  roof 
nor  walls.  Only  a  pile  of  rough-hewn  rocks  in  the  wilds 
of  the  desert,  exposed  to  the  storms  and  snow  and  sleet 
in  a  climate  of  perpetual  winter.  For  moments  the  sun- 
shine would  break  through  the  gray  clouds  and  make  the 
landscape  sparkle  into  diamonds  and  crystals  of  icy  gran- 
deur. But  those  that  worshiped  there  counted  it  as  naught. 
They  watched  the  wreaths  of  sand  as  they  rose  in  many  a 
whirl,  or  the  fall  of  the  snowflakes,  and  made  records  of 
it  all.  On  the  altar  were  two  idols,  cut  out  of  granite,  — 
Simplicity  and  Necessity,  grim  to  look  at.  To  them  they 
offered,  to  my  horror,  human  sacrifices,  their  own  children. 
But  so  the  idols  craved ;  and  many  fond  hopes,  many  warm 
desires,  many  tender  sentiments  went  up  in  smoke  on  the 
rock-bound  altar.  As  I  stayed  I  became  impressed  with 
the  absolute  democracy  of  the  religion  —  the  democracy 
of  absolute  poverty  and  absolute  law  —  and  their  willing- 
ness to  sacrifice  all  to  what  seemed  to  me  mere  idols. 

So  impressed  was  I  with  the  simplicity  and  sternness  and 
cold  awfulness  of  it  that  my  inner  self  seemed  to  shrink 
within  me  to  a  mere  ghost  of  its  former  puffed-up  state. 
I  felt  so  impressed  with  the  uncompromising,  relentlessly 
democratic  character  of  the  forces  of  the  universe  and  my 
own  insignificance  as  a  finite  individual,  that  when  their 
priests  told  me  that  to  please  their  gods  I  must  sacrifice 
all  that  I  loved,  I  threw  into  the  fire  many  of  my  conceits, 
many  subjective  breedings  and  many  a  petty  desire  —  but 
not  all  that  I  loved,  and  so  I  could  not  become  a  member 
of  the  fraternity.  But  sometime,  I  dare  say,  I  shall  go 
out  again  into  the  wilds,  where  I  can  feel  the  tonic  of  the 


12  Truth  and  Reality 

north  wind  and  admire  again  the  bleak  solemnity  of  the 
scene. 

But  I  could  not  stay  there  always.  I  need  to  get  back 
to  the  society  of  Kant  and  Fichte  and  Browning  and  the 
rest  who  have  felt  that  circumstance  is  to  some  extent 
plastic  in  the  service  of  ideals  and  that  we  shall  not  utterly 
perish,  at  least  not  without  having  our  say.  The  temple 
where  I  spend  most  of  my  time  is  an  unfinished  Gothic 
sort  of  structure,  where  many  artists  are  at  work,  each  in 
his  own  way.  I  was  introduced  to  the  group  by  a  friend 
of  mine,  the  brilliant  and  human  William  James,  who  spent 
a  lifetime  trying  to  provide  a  framework,  and  who  is  now 
at  work  on  some  plans  for  the  interior.  It  is  a  place  where 
everybody  has  something  to  do.  Each  one  is  allowed  to 
choose  his  own  task,  make  his  own  plan  and  fix  his  own 
salary.  There  is  no  supervision  as  yet ;  in  fact  the  plan  is 
that  there  shall  be  no  supervision  of  the  work  as  a  whole. 
This  is  looked  at  askance  by  outsiders,  and  mutiny  is 
prophesied.  What  can  be  the  worth  of  the  work  thus 
pursued  ?  And  how  can  a  man  be  allowed  to  draw  on 
the  universe  according  to  his  own  estimate  ?  A  system  of 
grading  has  been  suggested  to  ascertain  the  fitness  of  plan 
and  work.  But  so  far  no  available  tribunal  has  been  found 
except  the  succession  of  workers  themselves  and  what 
appeals  to  them.  Each  artist  is  thus  his  own  judge  of 
fitness,  and  when  he  is  superseded,  there  seems  to  be  no 
guarantee  that  his  work  will  be  carried  on.  But  as  the 
workers  are  conscious  of  each  other's  plans,  and  as  new 
artists  serve  apprenticeships  under  old  masters,  it  is  ex- 
pected that  there  will  be  a  degree  of  continuity  and  unity. 

But  after  all,  the  center  of  interest  in  this  religion  is 
not  the  temple,  but  the  artists.  The  temple  may  never  be 


Philosophic  Tolerance  13 

finished,  as  each  artist  and  each  generation  of  artists  modify 
the  plans  to  suit  their  own  ideals.  But  the  artists  get  prac- 
tice, and  the  temple  is  first  of  all  a  school  for  artists.  And 
each  artist  is  paid  at  least  through  the  joy  of  the  working 
and  the  appreciation  he  feels  for  such  momentary  beauty 
as  he  can  produce. 

Here  at  least  the  artist  has  the  sense  of  doing  some- 
thing, for  in  the  other  temples  there  is  nothing  to  do  but 
contemplate  that  which  is,  whether  beauty  or  desert.  Here 
worship  is  work  and  work  is  worship.  Perhaps  somehow, 
somewhere  and  sometime  his  work  may  mean  more  than 
he  knows.  Perhaps  an  unseen  Artist  may  be  piecing  to- 
gether from  moment  to  moment  the  scattered  fragments 
of  our  insight.  If  the  artist  gets  disheartened,  and  if  his 
work  and  fellow-workers  do  not  offer  sufficient  encourage- 
ment, with  the  strenuous  Kant  working  away  at  the  fresco 
of  his  dark  corner,  and  young  Fichte  with  untamed  en- 
thusiasm trying  to  boss  the  job,  and  the  lovable  James 
preaching  his  favorite  principle  of  pragmatism,  and  other 
heroic  souls,  "each  in  his  own  tongue"  —  if  all  of  these 
sometimes  fail  to  please,  and  work  becomes  irksome,  let 
him  go  into  the  temple  of  beauty,  in  the  fairy  land  of 
summer,  and  rest  awhile.  And  if  he  gets  too  absorbed 
in  his  own  plans  to  be  tolerant  of  other  workers,  I  should 
advise  him  to  go  out  to  that  lonely  rock-bound  altar  in  the 
wilds,  and  there  learn  to  sacrifice  his  subjective  conceits 
and  to  respect  law  and  order. 

In  the  absorption  of  my  meditation,  the  glowing  coals 
of  the  grate  fire  have  turned  to  ashes.  The  snowflakes 
have  ceased  to  fall ;  and  the  brisk  zero  temperature 
beckons  me  into  God's  out-of-doors.  The  spell  of  revery 
is  over;  and  instead  of  dreamy  sympathy,  I  feel  the  call 


14  Truth  and  Reality 

to  stern  activity  —  to  conquer  the  world  in  my  own  Norse 
way.  I  realize  now  that  whatever  our  moods  and  sym- 
pathies, they  do  not  make  our  ideas  come  true.  This 
must  be  tested  by  their  ability  to  lead  us  in  the  direction 
of  the  intended  facts  —  to  guide  conduct.  But  I  hope 
that  I  shall  not  forget  after  to-day  that  I,  too,  am  a  being 
of  moods  and  temperamental  limitations ;  and  that  in  the 
gentle  school  of  friendship  and  appreciation  I  may  be  the 
better  able  to  discriminate  sanely  and  create  truly. 

We  should  be  tolerant,  not  because  there  is  no  such 
thing  as  truth,  but  because,  under  the  limitations  of  human 
nature,  it  is  important  that 

Each  from  his  separate  star 
Shall  draw  the  thing  as  he  sees  it 
For  the  God  of  things  as  they  are, 

so  he  does  it  conscientiously,  using  all  the  cautions  that 
the  technique  of  truth  provides.  The  race,  in  its  historic 
experience,  will  eventually  pass  upon  the  individual  insight, 
and  reject  or  incorporate  into  its  institutional  network, 
according  as  it  explains  or  simplifies  life.  Even  now  we 
like  to  think  that  somehow,  somewhere,  there  is  a  per- 
sonality, whose  insight  is  as  wide  as  the  facts;  whose 
sympathy  can  embrace  the  variety  of  nature  and  human 
nature ;  and  whose  sanity  can  give  each  tendency  and 
mood  its  proper  place,  in  the  infinite  perspective  of  his- 
tory. To  this  ideal  Socius,  however  incomprehensible 
his  existence,  we  must  finally  entrust  our  fragmentary 
insight.  But  we  half-men,  while  we  struggle  and  see 
through  a  glass,  darkly,  should  at  least  make  our  tolerance 
as  large  as  our  ignorance. 


CHAPTER   II 

MIND  AS  INSTINCT 

THE  thesis  I  wish  to  maintain  in  this  chapter,  for  purposes 
of  simplification,  is  that  all  of  our  fundamental  adjustments 
or  categories,  viewed  from  the  point  of  view  of  individual 
development,  are  instinctive  or  organic  adjustments ;  that 
the  stimuli,  which  constitute  the  environment,  are  simply 
the  occasion  for  calling  into  play  the  structural  tendencies 
of  the  organic  growth  series,  and  that  such  categories  as 
recapitulation,  imitation,  and  accommodation  are  pseudo- 
categories,  stating  certain  results  from  the  point  of  view 
of  another  consciousness,  but  not  explanatory  of  the  real 
process  of  consciousness.  This  I  believe  to  apply  to  the 
whole  history  of  individual  consciousness,  and  not  simply 
to  its  initial  stages.  If  this  thesis  is  true,  progress  must 
take  place  through  spontaneous  variations  and  natural 
selection,  though  tendencies  must  be  made  definite  and 
effective  through  external  stimuli  and  the  process  of 
experience.  The  possibility  of  education  is  determined 
by  our  evolutionary  heritage.  Whether  natural  selection 
alone  or  other  agencies  must  be  called  in  to  account  for 
this  heritage,  we  must  leave  open  here.  Natural  selection, 
at  any  rate,  is  evident  enough  both  in  society  and  nature ; 
and  it  must  act  upon  such  grist  as  spontaneous  variations. 
Some  of  these  variations,  the  mutations,  in  the  process  of 
heredity  evidently  stick. 

The  old  idea  of  the  evolution  of  consciousness  as  a  con- 

15 


1 6  Truth  and  Reality 

tinuous  series,  statable  in  terms  of  simpler  processes  from 
which  the  more  complex  were  supposed  to  be  compounded, 
has  gradually  become  a  thing  of  the  past.  Sensationalism, 
simple  and  plausible  as  it  seemed,  has  been  proven  inade- 
quate, and  psychology  is  now  looking  not  to  chemistry,  but 
to  evolutionary  biology,  for  its  cue.  The  reason  for  the 
discontinuity  of  the  psychic  series  or  its  leaps  and  starts  is 
that  psychological  process  waits  upon  biological  structure ; 
and  only  when  the  biological  conditions  are  complete  do 
the  new  forms  of  consciousness  leap  forth  as  mysteriously 
as  the  wonders  in  rubbing  Aladdin's  lamp.  The  lamp  is 
the  thing,  and  just  that  kind  of  lamp,  though  of  course  the 
magic  result  would  not  follow  unless  the  lamp  were  rubbed. 
With  the  perfection  of  the  mechanism  of  the  eye,  and  the 
complicated  structural  conditions  for  sight,  light  leaps  into 
being.  So  with  the  mechanism  of  the  ear  and  the  won- 
drous world  of  sound. 

The  stages  of  consciousness  are  abrupt,  however  graded 
may  be  the  development  of  the  structural  conditions.  First 
of  all,  whether  there  is  prenatal  consciousness  or  not,  con- 
sciousness waits  upon  certain  antecedent  structural  condi- 
tions before  it  appears  at  all.  Before  the  appearance  of 
consciousness  the  foetus,  in  response  to  certain  stimuli  of 
temperature  and  blood  supply,  has  already  unfolded  a  struc- 
tural series  embodying  the  /evolutionary  results  of  varia- 
tions and  survival  of  untold  ages.  But  the  unfolding  of 
structural  characteristics  does  not  stop  with  the  appearance 
of  the  first  vague  consciousness.  In  obedience  to  stimuli, 
intra-  and  extra-organic,  the  organism  continues  to  grow 
and  to  develop  new  structural  characteristics,  and  as  the 
structural  conditions  reach  certain  stages  of  complexity 
there  appear  new  forms  of  conscious  response.  Let  us  for 


Mind  as  Instinct  17 

our  purpose  state  the  dramatic  stages  as  three  :  First,  sen- 
sitiveness or  immediate  consciousness ;  secondly,  associative 
memory  and  expectancy ;  thirdly,  reflection,  the  analyzing 
out  or  making  focal,  to  use  Lloyd  Morgan's  term,  certain 
relations  and  abstracting  them  for  the  better  manipulation 
of  the  concrete  situation.  Now  the  thesis  here  maintained 
is  that  the  successive  appearance  of  each  of  these  stages 
of  development,  with  all  their  intermediaries,  is  equally  or- 
ganic and  abrupt,  the  unfolding  or  growth  of  a  structural 
series  in  obedience  to  certain  stimuli,  which  do  not  make 
the  series  any  more  than  the  heat  of  the  incubator  makes 
the  chicken,  but  which  are  simply  the  conditions  calling 
forth  the  series ;  the  stages  of  development  from  first  to 
last,  as  well  as  what  stimuli  are  effective,  being  determined 
by  the  nature  of  the  organism,  which  again  is  what  it  is  as 
a  result  of  spontaneous  variation  and  natural  selection. 

It  is  wrong  to  suppose  with  many  recent  psychologists 
and  biologists  that  the  human  brain  is  essentially  unor- 
ganized and  that  the  environment  organizes  it.  The  envi- 
ronment, whether  physical  or  social,  can  only  furnish  stimuli. 
The  human  brain  has  far  more  complex  structural  tenden- 
cies than  that  of  any  other  being.  But  while  the  brain  of 
the  animals  below  man  has  a  comparatively  short  dynamic 
span  and  the  few  instincts  appear  practically  together  and 
mature  shortly  after  birth,  the  human  organism  has  a  long 
dynamic  span,  with  an  organic  series  of  instincts  maturing 
in  a  certain  order.  Natural  selection  has  here  pro- 
vided for  an  hierarchy  of  instincts.  But  the  law  of  devel- 
opment is  the  same :  a  certain  congenital  structural  order 
unfolds  itself  in  response  to  certain  stimuli.  That  this 
structural  development  is  in  response  largely  to  post-natal 
and  extra-organic  stimuli  in  the  human  being  does  not  alter 


1 8  Truth  and  Reality 

the  instinctive  character  of  the  process.  If  we  define  in- 
stinct as  a  response  to  stimulus  determined  by  congenital 
structure,  then  we  may  reduce  all  the  stages  of  mental 
process  to  the  category  of  instinct.  The  only  question  is 
as  between  earlier  and  later  or  simpler  and  more  complex 
stages  of  instincts.  What  must  not  be  forgotten  is  that  the 
growth  order  of  our  instincts,  as  well  as  the  number  of  our 
instincts,  is  congenital. 

Nothing  fills  me  with  more  amazement  than  this  pro- 
vision of  nature  for  a  growth  span,  in  which  the  series  of 
instincts  is  called  forth  in  its  due  order  at  the  beck  of  the 
environment.  The  first  great  departure  which  nature 
makes  from  the  animals,  where  maturity  sits  close  on  birth, 
is  to  stretch  out  the  period  of  infancy.  This  permits  the 
nervous  system,  with  its  capacity  for  habit  and  memory,  to 
develop  in  the  presence  of  the  stimuli  upon  which  it  must 
act,  instead  of  starting  ready  made.  With  this  equipment 
and  this  prolongation  of  growth,  nature  makes  necessary 
the  first  great  social  institution  —  the  family.  But  nature 
does  not  stop  here.  In  order  to  provide  for  the  proper 
staging  of  the  ideals  and  sentiments,  so  indispensable  for 
the  complexer  demands  of  civilization,  nature  splices  in 
the  period  of  adolescence,  with  its  emotional  plasticity,  its 
enthusiasm  and  loyalty ;  and  this  period  is  being  ever  pro- 
longed to  meet  the  increasing  social  demands  for  adjust- 
ment. How  it  is  that  a  growth  order  can  be  inherited,  and  in 
what  way  the  seemingly  indefinite  protoplasmic  material 
can  develop  in  mere  response  to  stimuli  a  series  of  ten- 
dencies, is  as  dark  as  is  the  problem  of  causation  generally, 
and  of  transmission  of  characteristics  at  all  in  particular. 
We  do  not  doubt,  however,  the  innateness  of  the  sexual 
response,  though  it  is  conditioned  in  the  case  of  a  human 


Mind  as  Instinct  19 

being  by  a  complex  and  long  series  of  structural  growth. 
This  one  instance  ought  to  convince  us  that  the  survival 
variations  operate  not  only  sectionally,  but  longitudinally  in 
the  stream  of  development.  The  absurd  supposition  of  the 
English  empiricists  that  innate  is  synonymous  with  that 
with  which  we  are  born  and  that  the  rest  is  acquired,  is 
once  and  for  all  exploded  by  biology.  Development  before 
and  after  birth  is  due  alike  to  an  inner  structural  tendency 
unfolding  in  response  to  stimuli. 

To  suppose,  therefore,  as  contemporary  psychology  still 
largely  does,  that  the  higher  mental  activities  are  compli- 
cations of  lower  activities;  that,  for  example,  associative 
memory  is  simply  the  result  of  sensation?  and  habit ;  that 
concepts  are  only  a  specific  kind  of  mechanical  association, 
and  that  thus  the  higher  strata  of  experience  are  built  right 
up  from  the  lower,  is  simply  substituting  chemical  meta- 
phors for  explanation.  If  images  were  the  complication 
of  sensations  merely,  why  is  it  that  some  of  the  animals 
lower  in  the  scale,  which  show  signs  of  sensation  and 
habit,  never  acquire  images  ?  They  must  have  sensations 
enough  —  probably  a  larger  variety  than  Helen  Keller. 
And,  again,  if  concepts  and  judgments  are  simply  associa- 
tions, why  is  it  that  animals  with  complex  associative  mech- 
anism do  not  show  any  sign  of  abstract  analysis?  It  is 
surely  not  the  fault  of  stimuli,  as  they  are  surrounded  by 
the  same  world  in  which  we  exist,  hear  the  same  sounds 
and  have  the  same  variety  of  light  and  color.  The  higher 
types  of  reaction  are  not  compounded  out  of  the  simpler, 
though  they  may  presuppose  these.  They  are  the  result 
of  structural  development,  not  merely  of  functional  adap- 
tation. Given  the  inner  structural  equipment,  and  we  can- 
not help  remembering  and  reasoning,  when  the  proper 


2O  Truth  and  Reality 

stimuli  are  furnished,  but  without  that  stimuli  are  of  no 
avail.  Let  us  now  inquire  a  little  more  in  detail  into  the 
stages  of  instinct. 

STAGES     OF     DEVELOPMENT     AND     THEIR     CHARACTERISTIC 

INSTINCTS 

Each  of  the  stages  or  leaps  of  development  mentioned 
above,  sensitiveness,  associative  memory  and  reflection, 
has  its  own  characteristic  instincts,  which  emerge  with  the 
structural  growth  of  which  the  above  stages  of  conscious- 
ness are  the  coefficients.  I  do  not  deny  that  there  are 
intermediary  stages  less  dramatic,  but  those  we  can  afford 
for  our  purposes  to  neglect.  Nor  must  I  be  understood 
as  holding  that  associative  memory  and  reflection  are  in 
any  sense  creative  of  instincts.  On  the  contrary,  the  later 
instincts  may  be  said  to  be  creative  of  them.  They  are 
simply  the  structural  machinery  which  has  proved  service- 
able, if  not  essential,  in  the  unfolding  of  certain  instincts, 
and  hence  this  machinery  has  been  grafted  on  the  instincts 
or  become  congenital. 

I.    The  Sensitive  Stage  and  the  Primary  Instincts 

The  instincts  on  the  sensitive  stage,  and  before  that  on 
the  merely  physiological,  are  relatively  simple  and  general 
in  character.  They  correspond  to  a  relatively  primitive 
environment. 

Looked  at  from  a  later  point  of  view  they  are  altogether 
egoistic,  i.e.,  they  have  to  do  with  individual  preservation, 
in  the  way  of  defensive  and  food-getting  series  of  reflexes. 
An  intricate  series  of  structural  adaptations  has  become 
purely  mechanical  when  we  have  a  chance  to  observe, 


***** 

.•r-f— 

€Uv  ex. 


Mind  as  Instinct  21 

such  as  the  machinery  for  digestion,  circulation,  breathing, 
etc.  If  natural  selection,  acting  upon  spontaneous  varia- 
tions, has  been  able  to  perfect  such  a  network  of  interre- 
lated processes,  with  such  continuity  of  operation  as  we 
find,  for  example,  in  digestion,  from  the  preparatory  seizing, 
deglutition  and  swallowing  until  the  substances  are  con- 
verted into  blood  or  carried  off  as  excrement,  we  ought  not 
to  be  staggered  at  the  thought  that  our  adjustments  in 
general  are  a  chain  forged  by  natural  selection  and  simply 
rattled  off  by  the  environment,  making  due  allowance  for 
the  mechanical  character  of  this  figure. 

The  instincts  that  are  usually  credited  to  a  human  infant 
are  such  as  grasping,  sucking,  crying  and  sneezing.  A 
comparison  is  drawn  between  the  human  infant  and  the 
chicken,  for  example,  to  the  advantage  of  the  latter.  That 
is  misleading,  however,  as  the  human  chick  is  still  being 
fledged  in  response  to  external  stimuli.  Thus  the  develop- 
ment of  sense  and  motor  coordinations,  and  the  coordina- 
tions of  the  senses  with  each  other  during  the  first  weeks 
of  the  human  infant,  are  no  less  instinctive,  though  they 
take  place  partly  in  response  to  extra-organic  stimuli.  It 
is  the  growth  series  of  the  organism  that  produces  the  in- 
stincts. The  extra-organic  stimuli  stand  in  no  different 
relation  to  the  child  than  do  the  prenatal  stimuli  to  the 
chicken.  The  superiority  of  the  child's  development  lies 
in  the  larger  range  of  its  stimuli,  not  in  its  less  instinctive 
character.  The  same  may  be  said  of  the  more  complex 
motor  coordinations  for  walking.  These  are  not  learned  by 
experience.  They  developed  even  when  an  absurd  system 
of  swaddling  clothes  prevented  functional  adaptation.  So 
with  the  development  of  speech.  The  conduct  of  the  gar- 
rulous human  environment  merely  furnishes  stimuli  for 


22  Truth  and  Reality 

more  definite  response  by  the  developing  speech  centers. 
The  human  being  is  simply  a  long  time  being  fledged. 
We  may  say  that  the  infant  reactions  at  the  outset  are 
more  general  than  those  of  the  chicken,  though  here  too 
we  have  to  be  cautious,  as  the  reactions  of  the  chicken  are 
probably  much  more  general  than  was  supposed  by  early 
investigators.  The  chicken,  according  to  Morgan,  does 
not  have  a  special  response  for  the  hawk,  though  it  has  a 
certain  response  for  a  certain  kind  of  stimuli  that  cause 
instinctive  terror. 

If  we  look  at  the  conscious  side  of  the  more  primitive 
instinctive  adjustments,  we  find  ourselves  on  a  rather  specu- 
lative foundation.  Where  consciousness  is  not  efficient, 
its  presence  must  naturally  be  conjectural,  and  a  large 
number  of  reactions  not  only  in  the  lower  animals  but  in 
human  beings  can  be  treated  as  tropisms.  The  going  off 
of  the  early  instincts  is  largely  a  penny-in-the-slot  affair,  to 
use  Lloyd  Morgan's  figure.  Consciousness  is  at  first  at 
most  a  spectator.  If  consciousness  is  present,  the  proper 
working  of  the  slot  is  accompanied  by  a  pleasure  value, 
the  improper  by  pain.  Thus  likes  and  dislikes,  on  one 
hand,  and  reactions,  advantageous  and  disadvantageous 
to  the  organism,  on  the  other,  tend  to  coincide.  But  it 
would  be  wrong  on  that  account  to  regard  pleasure-pain  as 
legislative  in  the  evolution  of  instincts;  for,  on  the  one 
hand,  complex  structural  adaptations  exist  which  seem 
purely  physiological,  and,  on  the  other  hand,  where  pleas- 
ure and  pain  now  indicate  survival  value,  it  is  simply 
because,  as  a  result  of  the  sorting  of  natural  selection,  they 
have  survived.  Where  the  environment  changes  rapidly 
and  where  the  law  of  natural  selection  has  not  chance  to 
operate,  pleasure  and  pain  are  not  sufficient  guides.  Wit- 


Mind  as  Instinct  23 

ness  the  cows  transplanted  to  South  America,  which  took 
pleasure  in  poisonous  weeds,  and  the  birds  on  the  South 
Sea  Islands  spoken  of  by  Darwin,  which  lacking  the 
instinct  of  fear  toward  man  paid  the  penalty  until  they 
either  were  exterminated  or  established  the  instinct.  Wit- 
ness, too,  the  large  number  of  pleasures  in  human  beings,  such 
as  indulgence  in  opium,  alcoholic  liquors,  and  various  forms 
of  sexual  excess  which  are  pernicious  and  on  which  the 
law  of  natural  selection  has  yet  failed  to  operate.  Pleas- 
ure and  pain  have  indeed  become  a  vital  part  of  the  func- 
tionirfg  of  some  instincts,  though  of  others  not.  It  surely 
would  be  absurd  to  try  to  state  our  primary  instinctive 
reactions  in  terms  of  mere  subjective  teleology,  as  some 
seem  inclined  to  do  at  present. 

The  stimuli  which  make  the  slot  work  may  be  qualitative 
differences,  such  as  loud  sounds  or  brilliant  lights,  or  they 
may  be  behavior  stimuli,  which  call  forth  similar  move- 
ments in  the  individual.  But  in  either  case  we  have 
simply  a  stimulus  as  setting  off  a  congenital  mechanism. 
The  reaction  on  behavior  stimuli  is  sometimes  called  imi- 
tation. But  this  is  the  significance  of  the  reaction  to  the 
psychologist,  who  compares  it  with  the  behavior  stimulus. 
It  is  not  imitation  or  accommodation  to  the  child  or  animal. 
It  is  simply  a  case  of  a  fascinating  stimulus,  which  is  only 
another  name  for  fitting  the  slot  and  the  slot  going  off. 
Interest  always  waits  on  tendency.  If  the  child  prove  to 
deviate  or  to  be  original  in  its  imitation,  from  the  specta- 
tor's point  of  view,  that  is  because  it  does  not  imitate  but 
responds  to  the  stimulus  in  a  way  dictated  by  its  structural 
tendencies.  If  it  continues  the  process,  that  is  not  for  the 
sake  of  approximation,  but  because  given  such  structural 
tendencies  it  cannot  help  repeating  the  conduct.  The  con- 


24  Truth  and  Reality 

scious  imitation  of  a  copy  marks  a  late  stage  in  human 
development. 

Sometimes  instincts  are  explained  as  recapitulation,  and 
they  do  indeed  have  a  long  survival  history  back  of  them. 
But  to  call  them  recapitulatory  is  again  the  point  of  view 
of  the  external  observer  who  compares  the  reactions  with 
those  of  ancestors.  The  individual  on  the  level  of  sensi- 
tive consciousness  at  any  rate  does  not  act  to  recapitulate 
his  ancestors.  The  spring  for  the  action  must  be  found 
in  his  own  organic  machinery,  whether  it  agrees  or  dis- 
agrees with  that  of  his  ancestors.  There  is  no  such  thing 
as  evolution  in  the  sense  of  simply  marching  the  old  cate- 
gories upon  the  stage  again  as  implied  in  recapitulation. 
The  machinery  for  imitation,  accommodation  and  recapitu- 
lation exists  only  when  the  individual  has  in  mind  a  copy 
of  the  behavior  of  others,  whether  past  or  present.  But 
even  on  that  level  the  springs  for  the  action  must  be  sought 
in  the  individual  structural  tendencies.  He  does  not  imi- 
tate because  of  imitation  or  recapitulate  because  of  recapitu- 
lation, but  because  he  is  wound  up  in  such  a  way  that  such 
stimuli  appeal  to  him  or  set  him  off.  Such  categories  as 
imitation,  accommodation  and  recapitulation  are  not  ex- 
planatory categories;  they  are  simply  comparisons  as  made 
by  an  observer  external  to  the  process.  They  are  pseudo- 
categories. 

Instincts,  on  the  sensitive  level,  are  made  definite  by 
trial  and  habit.  The  instinct  puts  forth  a  succession  of 
efforts  to  attain  its  vague  end.  These  efforts  are  first 
random.  By  a  law,  as  organic  as  instinct  itself,  the  suc- 
cessful efforts  are  emphasized  by  the  organism;  the 
unsuccessful  are  weeded  out,  until  gradually  a  definite 
habit  is  forged. 


Mind  as  Instinct  2$ 

2.    Associative  Memory  and  the  Secondary  Instincts 

While  the  stimuli  are  playing  the  primary  tendencies 
and  under  the  shelter  of  the  parental  and  other  social 
instincts  of  the  individuals  of  its  immediate  environment, 
the  organism  is  busy  perfecting  the  structure  for  the  later 
instincts  with  their  more  complex  machinery.  These  we 
may  call  secondary,  though  that  does  not  mean  that  they 
are  less  instinctive.  They  only  presuppose  a  greater  struc- 
tural differentiation.  Lloyd  Morgan  speaks  of  the  mother 
hen  protecting  the  chick  from  the  law  of  natural  selection. 
That  is  true  in  the  chick's  individual  capacity,  but  we  must 
not  forget  that  it  is  as  a  result  of  natural  selection  that  the 
parent  has  its  parental  instincts  which  shelter  the  newly 
developed  chick.  Before  the  chick  has  social  feelings  it 
has  the  shelter  of  social  feelings.  Else  there  would  be 
neither  hen  nor  chickens  to  survive.  Natural  selection 
has  operated  to  produce  a  group  supplementation  of  in- 
stincts. It  can  thus  telescope  the  undeveloped  structure 
into  the  later  structures  of  other  individuals,  at  the  same 
time  providing  in  the  behavior  of  the  more  developed 
members  of  the  group  the  stimuli  to  call  off  the  dynamic 
tendencies  of  the  immaturer  developing  structure,  thus 
lengthening  the  dynamic  span  and  increasing  its  develop- 
mental possibilities. 

It  must  be  remembered,  however,  that  the  social  environ- 
ment occupies  exactly  the  same  relation  to  the  develop- 
mental series  as  the  physical.  It  can  only  furnish  the 
occasion  or  stimuli  for  setting  off  the  dynamic  series. 
There  is  no  social  heritage  in  any  other  sense  than  there 
is  a  physical  heritage,  a  set  of  stimuli,  pennies  for  the  slot 
that  will  make  it  go  off,  if  they  fit.  Social  institutions,  like 


26  Truth  and  Reality 

physical  stimuli,  must  be  the  counterpart  of  our  instinctive 
tendencies  to  be  of  significance  for  us.  They  must  be  our 
inner  needs  and  dispositions  objectified,  if  we  are  to  find 
ourselves  in  them.  Else  they  become  a  handicap,  not  stim- 
uli for  our  self -development.  They  must  play  the  growth 
scale  of  instinct  in  its  proper  order ;  or  we  must  develop, 
as  best  we  can,  in  spite  of  them,  not  because  of  them.  In- 
deed there  could  be  no  stronger  testimony  to  the  innate 
character  of  mind  than  that  in  spite  of  all  the  abuses  of 
our  unpsychological  methods  of  education  —  the  abstrac- 
tions of  the  alphabet  and  the  multiplication  table  —  the 
human  mind  develops  true  to  its  nature. 

Looked  at  from  the  point  of  view  of  race  history,  the 
mechanism  for  associative  memory  must  be  regarded  as  a 
lucky  variation  or  an  accumulation  of  variations  which 
make  it  possible  to  live  an  experience  again,  given  an  in- 
ternal or  external  cue ;  which  make  it  possible,  therefore, 
to  guide  the  present  beck  of  stimuli  with  reference  to  con- 
sequences of  past  experience,  thus  making  instinct  more 
definite  and  serviceable,  a  reaction  on  particulars  and  not 
merely  on  a  vague  kind.  The  survival  value  of  such  an 
organic  leap  must  have  been  momentous.  For  whatever 
history  of  accumulations  of  survival  this  machinery  may 
represent  on  its  structural  side,  from  the  point  of  view  of 
consciousness  it  is  a  radical  leap.  There  is  no  way  of  re- 
ducing efficient  consciousness  into  simply  more  conscious- 
ness of  the  concomitant  or  spectator  kind  ;  no  way  in 
which  the  play  of  immediate  impulse  with  its  simple  ma- 
chinery of  tedious  trial,  gradual  elimination,  and  dumb, 
monotonous  habit  can  be  made  to  yield  a  picture  of  the 
past  result  and  a  short  cut  to  reaction  on  the  basis  of  it. 
Using  the  penny-in-the-slot  illustration  again,  a  new  mech- 


Mind  as  Instinct  27 

anism  has  been  introduced  into  the  slot  that  not  only  makes 
the  slot  register  its  going  off,  but  also  uses  as  guide  the 
structural  picture  in  its  next  going  off. 

But  the  new  machinery  is  still  essentially  a  slot.  It  is 
conditioned  through  and  through  by  organic  tendencies : 
organic  tendency  in  the  form  of  instinct  conditions  interest ; 
organic  tendency  in  the  form  of  habit  makes  dynamic 
continuity  possible ;  and  organic  tendency  as  specialization 
of  structure  conditions  the  kinds  of  imagery  or  content  the 
operation  shall  have.  While  the  machinery,  therefore,  is 
vastly  more  complex  and  immensely  more  efficient  in  its 
greater  scope  of  coordination  and  its  greater  economy  of 
effort,  it  remains  as  organic  or  instinctive  in  character  as 
before. 

With  the  perfecting  of  the  machinery  of  associative 
memory  there  leap  into  being  in  their  proper  order  a  to- 
tally new  group  of  instincts,  the  social  instincts.  While 
these  instincts  are  conditioned  by  the  more  complex  struc- 
tural machinery,  that  does  not  mean  that  they  are  the 
result  of  associative  memory.  The  latter  might  make  us 
more  efficiently  egoistic,  but  could  not  change  our  funda- 
mental attitude.  The  social  instincts  are  rather  the  ratio- 
nale of  the  more  complex  machinery  than  vice  versa.  Only 
thus  could  the  social  instincts  become  efficient.  But  with 
these  instincts  and  the  associative  mechanism  the  individ- 
ual is  equipped  for  the  beginnings  of  group  life  with  new 
possibilities  and  necessities  of  survival  variations. 

That  associative  memory  and  the  fundamental  social 
instincts  are  interdependent  is  shown  not  only  by  observ- 
ing the  coincident  appearance  of  the  two  in  the  develop- 
ment series,  but  more  conclusively  by  the  vivisectional  and 
pathological  methods.  In  the  experiments  of  the  removal 


28  Truth  and  Reality 

of  the  hemispheres  of  the  dog,  the  pigeon,  and  the  frog, 
for  example,  it  has  been  shown  that  all  social,  which  here 
means  primarily  sexual,  response  vanishes,  together  with 
associative  memory.  The  same  is  shown  in  widespread 
injury  to  the  human  brain,  in  such  a  case  as  that  cited  in 
Huxley's  essay  on  Animal  Automatism,  and  in  the  recent 
case  in  Paris  of  a  human  being  born  without  hemispheres. 
If  we  regard  the  matter  merely  logically,  it  is  hard  to  see 
what  social  could  mean  apart  from  representation,  though 
representation  can  be  conceived  without  sociability.  But 
while  the  social  instincts  thus  wait  upon  a  certain  structural 
development,  that  makes  them  no  less  organic  and  funda- 
mental in  nature. 

There  are,  properly  speaking,  no  such  things  as  social 
categories.  Imitation,  sympathy,  the  whole  list  of  sexual, 
parental  and  more  general  group  responses,  constituting 
social  fitness,  must  be  reduced  to  individual  variations, 
which  have  proved  to  have  survival  value  and  which  in 
turn  have  come  to  condition  the  survival  of  individuals  ex- 
ceptionally lacking  or  over-redundant  in  such  variations. 
What  environment  furnishes,  and  all  it  can  furnish,  is  the 
stimuli  and  the  survival  conditions. 

3.   Reflection  and  the  Tertiary  Strata  of  Instincts  —  the 
Ideals  or  Sentiments 

While  the  environment  is,  finally,  playing  the  primary 
and  secondary  instincts,  and  under  the  shelter  of  the  later 
ideal  tendencies  or  sentiments  of  the  group,  the  human 
organism  is  perfecting  its  structural  machinery  for  the 
issuance  of  a  new  set  of  instincts  —  demands  that  have  to 
do  with  the  unity  and  meaning  of  experience.  Given  a 


Mind  as  Instinct  29 

certain  complexity  of  our  registering  slot,  and  there  ap- 
pears the  power  of  analysis  and  abstraction.  This  again 
is  a  leap,  perhaps  the  most  wonderful  leap  of  all.  Con- 
sciousness by  a  new  device  is  able  to  hold  its  head  above 
the  passing  stream  and  survey  the  before  and  after.  It  no 
longer  merely  is  but  sees  the  passing  events.  From  the 
point  of  view  of  race  history  it  means  a  lucky  structural 
variation  or  accumulation  of  variations,  which  changed  the 
whole  course  of  evolution  by  giving  meaning  to  the  pro- 
cess and  thus  establishing  new  survival  values.  With  the 
individual,  however,  reasoning,  as  habit  and  associative 
memory,  is  congenital,  appearing  when  the  proper  struc- 
tural series  has  been  passed  through  in  response  to  the 
stimuli  of  the  environment,  which  now  first  become  prob- 
lems. The  idiot  cannot  learn  to  reason. 

Some  psychologists  have  held  that  reasoning  has  its 
beginning  in  language  and  that  it  is  in  language  that 
man  is  especially  superior  to  the  animals  below  him. 
But  language  in  some  form  can  exist  without  reasoning, 
as  is  shown  in  animal  life,  and  as  people's  creeds  and 
platforms  still  testify.  Given  the  structural  machinery 
for  abstraction,  and  language  becomes  an  indispensable 
instrument  and  so  has  developed  to  answer  the  demands 
of  reflection.  Nor  can  reason  or  meaning  be  reduced  to 
lower  forms  of  consciousness.  It  is  not  more  of  dreamy 
association,  however  complex  the  latter  may  become.  It 
is  a  new  attitude.  However  much  its  genesis  may  exceed 
our  comprehension,  we  have  now  the  structural  machinery 
for  holding  ourselves,  i.e.,  our  primary  and  secondary  in- 
stincts, at  arm's  length  and  looking  at  ourselves — a  mech- 
anism which  furnished  us  with  those  tools  by  means  of 
which  we  can  break  up  our  world  and  select  those  rela- 


3O  Truth  and  Reality 

tions  and  objects  that  have  meaning  and  value  for  us,  in- 
stead of  dealing  with  the  world  as  a  collection. 

With  the  structural  machinery  for  reason  there  appear 
a  new  group  of  tendencies,  demands  for  simplicity  and 
consistency,  for  unity  and  wholeness,  for  truth,  for  right, 
for  happiness,  for  beauty,  for  a  religious  and  philosophic 
setting  for  our  tendencies  or  needs.  From  the  vantage 
ground  of  this  new  structural  differentiation  the  primary 
and  secondary  instincts  can  be  surveyed  and  evaluated, 
and  a  whole  constituted.  Yet  our  bias  for  simplicity  and 
consistency,  our  sentiments  for  truth  and  beauty,  are  in 
their  deepest  roots  instinctive,  however  luminous  they 
have  made  the  pathway  of  life.  The  deepest  attitudes 
towards  the  universe  were  never  invented  by  man;  they 
are  not  the  result  of  a  consensus  of  opinion ;  they  are 
presupposed,  on  the  contrary,  in  all  our  reflections  upon 
life.  Without  them  we  should  not  have  raised  the  ques- 
tion of  why  and  wherefore  nor  have  felt  the  need  of  a 
consensus  of  opinion.  Our  highest  activities,  therefore, 
no  less  than  the  most  primitive,  move  within  instinct,  are 
the  response  of  our  organism  to  the  call  of  the  environ- 
ment Before  these  instinctive  demands  existed  there  was 
no  call,  for  the  environment  spoke  to  deaf  ears ;  there  was 
no  riddle  of  the  Sphinx,  only  a  vacant  stare;  no  order, 
but  only  the  passing  show  of  meaningless  events. 

It  has  been  said  as  a  criticism  against  Kant  that  his 
categories  are  shot  out  of  a  pistol.  This  is  true  of  reflec- 
tion generally,  as  well  as  its  fundamental  categories.  Re- 
flection, systematic  meaning,  when  it  appears,  is  not  more 
complex  associations  merely.  It  is  a  radically  new  atti- 
tude. It  did  not  grow  out  of  previous  non-reflective 
experience,  however  complex.  Stimuli,  intra-  and  extra- 


Mind  as  Instinct  31 

organic,  have  been  acting  upon  the  organism.  These 
have  been  the  occasion  for  the  organism  unfolding  its 
structural  series,  according  to  its  own  inner  dynamic  unity, 
until  at  the  beck  of  the  ever  active  environment  there  leaps 
forth  reason,  abruptly,  as  Athena  leaped  from  the  head  of 
Zeus,  and  mysteriously,  as  Aphrodite  rose  from  the  sea. 
The  self  is  awake  instead  of  dreaming.  This  could  not 
be  due  simply  to  the  call  of  the  environment,  for  that  has 
been  comparatively  stable.  Rather  the  reason  for  the  call 
being  a  call  must  be  sought  in  the  new  structural  conditions 

• 

perfected  for  the  purpose.  Just  as  sexual  love  appears  at 
a  certain  stage  of  development,  when  certain  structural 
conditions  have  been  completed,  and  a  totally  new  response 
is  made  to  old  stimuli,  so  reason  appears  suddenly  and  un- 
solicited, when  the  structural  series  reaches  a  certain  stage. 
We  ought  to  speak,  therefore,  of  falling  into  reflection  as 
we  speak  of  falling  in  love.  This  I  need  not  say  has 
nothing  to  do  with  Flechsig's  attempt  to  establish  a  dis- 
tinct anatomical  center  for  higher  mental  processes.  This 
theory  no  more  stands  or  falls  with  his  success  or  failure 
than  does  the  instinctive  character  of  sexual  love  with  the 
phrenological  bump  of  amativeness. 

What  has  been  said  of  the  more  general  categories  holds 
equally  for  the  more  particular  preferences  and  tastes  that 
go  to  differentiate  one  individual  from  other  individuals. 
Imitation  no  more  on  the  higher  than  on  the  lower  levels 
creates  tendencies  ;  but  a  certain  stimulus  is  the  fascinat- 
ing thing,  because  a  certain  structure  is  set  off.  The 
illuminating  sanity  of  James,  Royce's  esthetic  bias  for  an 
Hegelian  absolute,  and  Miinsterberg's  love  of  dialectic  — 
all  are  organic :  they  condition,  and  are  not  made  by,  en- 
vironmental stimuli.  There  is  a  certain  sameness  indeed 


32  Truth  and  Reality 

in  our  categories  and  preferences,  in  so  far  as  we  are  nor- 
mal, due  to  survival  conditions.  This  is  especially  true  of 
our  moral  tendencies,  which  would  be  especially  concerned. 
Beyond  the  dead  level,  however,  which  keeps  us  out  of  the 
penitentiary  or  the  insane  asylum,  our  tendencies  or  pref- 
erences vary  vastly.  Here  natural  selection  is  tolerant 
of  sports,  and  the  more  so  the  more  evolution  progresses. 
This  helps  us  to  understand  the  different  tastes  which 
become  creative  of  such  different  types  in  philosophy 
and  art.  It  also  accounts  for  the  utter  lack  of  finer 
esthetic  or  philosophic  appreciation  in  the  larger  number 
of  men.  These  are  so  far  aristocratic  variations.  Of 
course,  in  the  progress  of  civilization,  tendencies  such  as 
the  higher  esthetic  may  become  more  universal  as  an 
equipment  of  the  race;  and  "he  that  hath  no  music  in 
himself  "  may  in  such  a  state  of  society  be  regarded  as  "  fit 
for  treasons,  stratagems  and  spoils  "  and  dealt  with  accord- 
ingly. A  higher  moral  equipment,  at  any  rate,  is  gradually 
demanded. 

Yes,  if  we  are  poets  or  artists  or  philosophers  or  scien- 
tists at  all,  we  are  born  such,  and  not  only  to  the  class  but 
to  that  particular  type  that  individualizes  our  contribution 
from  that  of  others,  though  of  course  owing  to  a  defective 
environment  our  tendencies  may  never  be  played  so  as  to 
develop  the  possible  scale  of  values.  Only  the  other  day 
I  was  startled  by  the  striking  resemblance  between  a  cab- 
man and  a  great  philosopher  that  I  know.  Had  the  en- 
vironment played  the  scales  with  some  degree  of  skill,  the 
cabman  might  have  been  a  philosopher,  and  with  a  different 
set  of  stimuli  the  philosopher  might  have  been  a  cabman. 
Again,  we  find  too  often  those  lacking  evolutionary  qualifi- 
cations holding  down  the  job ;  and  men  without  philosophic 


Mind  as  Instinct  33 

insight  respond  with  a  feigned  adjustment  of  mere  words, 
as  the  color-blind  man  classifies  the  beautiful  world  of 
colors  in  his  own  series  of  dull  grays.  Sometimes  the  lack 
of  native  equipment  is  in  more  elementary  tendencies,  as  in 
the  incapacity  shown  by  some  people  for  the  rudiments  of 
number  or  language;  sometimes  it  seems  a  lack  of  the  more 
fundamental  moral  tendencies,  though  the  clumsy  and  un- 
natural order  of  our  stimuli  may  be  responsible  rather  than 
the  native  equipment.  Out  of  the  young  criminals  com- 
mitted to  the  Iowa  Industrial  School  at  Eldora  about  eighty 
per  cent  turn  out  honorable  men. 

If  we  say  that  what  is  native  is  docility,  then  at  least  we 
shall  have  to  use  the  plural  or  docilities,  because  docility 
in  one  direction  need  not  mean  docility  in  another.  But 
what  does  docility  mean  ?  Is  it  not  like  imitation,  a  mere 
name  for  a  result?  Is  not  man  docile  in  very  much  the 
same  sense  that  the  slot  is  when  the  proper  coin  is  put  in 
and  it  works?  A  man  may  be  docile  as  regards  things 
intellectual  and  not  in  things  esthetic,  to  one  kind  of  in- 
tellectual things  rather  than  to  another,  and  to  one  kind  at 
one  stage  of  his  development,  to  another  kind  at  another 
stage.  Docility,  then,  must  find  its  explanation  in  the  fact 
that  certain  tendencies  or  instincts  can  be  set  off  by  a  cer- 
tain kind  of  stimulus. 

While  the  machinery  of  reason  was  evolved  for  the  sake 
of  the  earlier  instincts  and  those  that  came  into  being  with 
it,  the  machinery  in  some  individuals,  as  a  result  again  of 
variation,  has  become  detached  from  the  earlier  strata  and 
runs  with  wheels  free.  This  is  one  of  the  forms  of  play, 
in  other  words,  and  the  mechanism  of  reflection  thus  sub- 
serves a  double  purpose,  that  of  coordinating  the  more 
primary  tendencies  and  that  of  mere  play,  whether  as  ab- 


34  Truth  and  Reality 

stract  reflection  and  system  making  or  perhaps  working  in 
the  more  picturesque  material  of  concrete  images,  instead 
of  words,  in  obedience  to  the  sentiment  for  the  beautiful. 
This  play  purpose  of  the  reflective  machinery  may  alto- 
gether eclipse  the  primary  purpose,  but  even  here  the  ma- 
chinery is  run  by  instinctive  demands. 

We  have  sketched  broadly  three  stages  of  mind  with 
their  characteristic  instincts  and  their  characteristic  mech- 
anism for  making  the  instincts  effective.  First,  the  stage 
of  physiological  or  sensitive  reaction,  where  consciousness 
is  a  mere  spectator.  Here  appear  the  egoistic-preservative 
instincts.  The  mechanism  here  is  trial  with  gradual  elim- 
ination and  habit.  Secondly,  the  stage  of  associative  mem- 
ory, where  an  image  d£  past  result  can  guide  the  reaction. 
Here  appear  the  social  instincts.  This  stage  is  vastly  su- 
perior to  the  preceding  in  its  coordination,  in  the  complex- 
ity of  its  instincts  and  the  economy  of  effort.  Last  of  all 
we  sketched  the  stage  of  reflective  meaning  with  the  ap- 
paratus for  survey,  for  selection,  abstraction  and  substitu- 
tion. With  this  appear  the  ideal  instincts  or  demands. 
We  have  seen  too  that  each  earlier  stage  as  a  result  of  nat- 
ural selection  can  be  telescoped  into  a  later  stage  of  the 
group  by  the  providential  arrangement  that  all  individuals 
are  not  of  the  same  age,  but  that  the  parents  by  the  virtue 
of  becoming  parents  have  developed  a  later  set  of  instincts, 
sheltering  the  offspring  in  their  earlier  stage  and  furnish- 
ing stimuli  for  the  development  of  the  structural  series. 
As  the  later  instincts  appear,  however,  the  earlier  are  tele- 
scoped into  the  later  in  the  same  individual  and  the  later 
become  the  guides  and  the  sheltering  foster-parents  of  the 
earlier.  Even  on  the  reflective  level  the  instinctive  stages 
retain  something  of  their  integrity.  We  are  not  always, 


Mind  as  Instinct  35 

indeed  very  seldom,  reasoning.  In  that  case  the  next 
lower  court  presides.  But  even  this  may  sleep  or  be  dis- 
attached  from  the  lower  centers,  and  then  the  lowest  pre- 
sides. Or,  taking  a  cross  section  of  the  reflective  stage, 
while  attention  selects  certain  aspects  as  focal,  in  the  mar- 
•ginal  field  we  shade  off  into  the  more  primitive  stages  of 
consciousness  through  border-line  associations  into  dim 
awareness.  And  so  the  stages  of  race  history  repeat  them- 
selves in  their  general  outlines,  not  only  in  the  stages  of 
individual  history,  but  every  day,  and,  in  fact,  coexist  in  one 
attention  moment,  the  whole  distance  from  tropism  to  re- 
flective  meaning. 


The  purpose  of  the  mechanism  of  instinct,  whether 
habit  or  associative  memory  or  abstraction,  is  to  make 
instinct  more  definite.  Instincts  are  at  first  universal. 
They  are  fitted  to  go  off  at  a  certain  kind  of  stimuli, 
on  the  lowest  level  a  very  vague  kind  indeed,  but  more 
limited  with  each  stage.  There  is  a  good  deal  of  differ- 
ence between  taste  in  general  and  taste  for  music.  Habit 
is  at  best  a  clumsy  device  for  limiting  the  kind,  but  mem- 
ory makes  possible  reaction  upon  a  particular,  while  the 
reflective  machinery  makes  possible  descriptive  definition. 

The  whole  series  of  life  can  thus  be  expressed  in  in- 
stinctive terms,  both  as  regards  content  and  mechanism  — 
meaning  by  instinctive  reaction  a  response  that  is  called 
off  as  a  result  of  organic  structure,  given  the  proper  stimu- 
lus. We  are  such  mechanisms  as  to  develop  in  a  certain 
structural  order  and  to  respond  at  certain  stages  in  certain 
characteristic  ways,  given  a  certain  range  and  order  of 
stimuli.  The  failure  to  call  forth  a  certain  tendency  in 
its  dynamic  order  may  fail  to  call  forth  other  tendencies, 
as  some  tendencies  are  dynamically  conditioned  upon  each 


36  Truth  and  Reality 

other.  Thus  the  failure  to  respond  to  sexual  love  must 
mean  the  failure  to  call  forth  the  paternal  tendencies,  and 
the  failure  to  present  the  situations  of  danger  and  sacrifice 
must  also  fail  to  call  forth  the  heroic  tendencies.  It  is 
here  that  we  are  helped  to  some  extent  at  least  by  the 
ideal  situations  of  poetry  and  art. 

I  realize  full  well  how  one-sided  and  mechanical  seems 
such  a  statement  of  the  evolution  of  mind.  The  structural 
side  of  the  process  is  but  one  side,  though  it  lends  itself 
most  easily  to  scientific  description.  The  whole  series  of 
evolutionary  forms  and  categories  must  be  understood  from 
the  point  of  view  of  creative  will,  which  through  a  variety 
of  efforts,  gradual  cumulations  or  sudden  mutations,  strives 
to  make  itself  definite  and  individual  and  which  gives  con- 
tinuity and  unity  to  the  process.  And  while  on  the  lower 
levels  of  life  we  may  have  to  be  satisfied  with  a  chemical 
statement  of  the  seemingly  accidental  variations,  may  it 
not  be  that  we  have  over-emphasized  physical  generation 
as  a  condition  for  variations  in  structure  ?  May  not  the  pas- 
sion and  birth  in  ideal  beauty  —  intense  moments  of  ideal 
creation  —  have  their  effect  upon  the  germ  cells,  as  they 
have  their  creative  effect  upon  the  later  life  of  the  individ- 
ual ?  It  may  be  a  provisional  bias,  due  to  our  experiment- 
ing with  lower  forms  of  life,  that  makes  us  look  upon  sexual 
generation  as  the  only  condition  of  plasticity.  There 
seems,  at  any  rate,  to  be  something  especially  plastic  about 
the  life  of  reason  as  contrasted  with  the  more  primitive  life 
of  habit  and  association.  We  know  little  about  the  condi- 
tions that  can  influence  the  germ  cells  —  those  bearers  of 
the  life  of  the  race ;  but  we  have  come  to  realize  more  and 
more  the  widespread  and  subtle  physiological  changes  of 
which  our  psychic  states,  especially  under  conditions  of 


\ 

Mind  as  Instinct  37 

high  intensity,  may  be  the  occasion.  May  it  not  be,  too, 
that  the  universe  itself  operates  as  an  artist  and  that  the 
blindness  of  the  process  lies  only  in  our  ignorance  ?  At 
any  rate,  the  continuity  of  the  building  out  of  structure 
must  be  sought  on  the  side  of  spontaneous  impulse,  not 
as  the  mere  mechanical  heaping  up  of  bricks  by  blind 
accident 

TENDENCY   AND    ENVIRONMENT 

It  is  jclear  now  that  the  nature  of  the  environment  and 
with  it  the  survival  value  of  tendencies  varies  at  each  stage 
of  development  In  the  early  stages  of  evolution,  survival 
is  a  matter  of  individual  fitness  based  upon  certain  primary 
tendencies  and  their  gradual  definition  by  means  of  habit. 
Then  the  social  tendencies  emerge  and  survival  value  must 
be  writ  in  tendencies  that  supplement  each  other  so  as  to 
make  group  life  possible.  The  primary  instincts  are  thus 
telescoped  into  the  more  complex  secondary  instincts  with 
their  mechanism  of  associative  memory.  Last  come  the 
ideal  instincts  that  appear  with  the  power  of  analysis  and 
abstraction,  and  primary  and  secondary  instincts  must  be 
telescoped  into  these  tertiary  instincts  in  order  to  meet  the 
conditions  of  survival.  With  each  stage  of  evolution  in- 
stincts become  more  numerous  and  complex,  and  as  the 
later  individuals  become  part  of  the  survival  conditions  to 
be  met,  the  survival  conditions  become  more  complex. 

It  must  be  kept  in  mind,  too,  that,  while  we  classify  our 
ideal  instincts  under  certain  large  genera,  such  as  feelings 
for  truth,  for  beauty,  for  right,  for  reverence,  etc.,  these 
are  only  large  rubrics  and  that  within  them  there  may 
be  any  number  of  instinctive  variations,  conditioning  our 
creativeness  and  appreciation.  Hence  our  realists  and 


38  Truth  and  Reality 

idealists  in  art,  our  tender-minded  and  tough-minded  in 
philosophy,  our  rigorists  and  hedonists  in  ethics,  our  Prot- 
estants and  Catholics  in  religion  —  in  brief  our  schools  with 
their  types  and  traditions  and  their  intolerance.  While  it 
is  true  that  imitation,  conventional  and  customary,  may 
lead  people  into  those  schools,  who  do  not  belong  there 
natively,  and,  therefore,  a  large  degree  of  uniformity  may 
be  obtained,  yet  it  is  also  true  that  such  types  of  feeling 
and  thought  would  not  have  arisen  in  the  first  place  and 
would  not  continue  indefinitely  through  the  ages,  if  they 
did  not  have  an  instinctive  basis  in  human  nature. 

With  greater  complexity  goes  also  greater  freedom  of 
development.  The  transmitting  of  variations  with  the 
progress  of  civilization  is  not  limited  to  those  immediately 
involved  in  survival ;  and  in  the  greater  differentiation  of 
labor  possible  under  an  industrial  regime,  survival  takes 
many  directions.  Thus  a  greater  variety  of  tastes  makes 
possible  a  wider  range  of  survival.  There  is  room  for  the 
musician  and  actor  and  sign-painter,  as  well  as  the  me- 
chanic. Then,  too,  the  instinct  of  pity  or  sympathy  shel- 
ters the  unfit,  for  the  time  being  at  least,  thus  complicating 
survival  conditions. 

Survival  conditions  never  change  more  rapidly  than  in 
a  civilized  environment.  While  in  one  generation  an  ar- 
tistic genius  starves  to  death  on  his  art,  in  another  he  can 
dictate  his  own  terms,  provided  his  style  of  art  becomes  a 
fad ;  while  in  one  generation  a  man  would  be  deemed  in- 
sane for  printing  or  making  furniture  by  hand,  when  fac- 
tories can  turn  out  as  serviceable  goods  by  the  millions, 
in  another  he  can  become  wealthy  and  famous  besides; 
while  in  one  generation  the  stake,  the  cross  and  the  gibbet 
cut  short  the  opportunity  of  the  heretic  from  propagating 


Mind  as  Instinct  39 

his  doctrines  and  the  species,  in  another  he  gets  the  praise 
of  men  and  the  fat  salaries,  while  the  orthodox  man  is 
doing  the  starving  stunt.  And  so  it  goes,  all  because  dif- 
ferent ages  produce  or  at  least  stimulate  different  tenden- 
cies—  because  in  one  age  the  backward  look,  in  another 
age  the  forward  look  predominates ;  because  the  mood  of 
humanity  varies. 

It  is  clear  that  Spencer's  idea  of  a  finite  static  environ- 
ment which  would  permit  of  absolute  adjustment  once  and 
for  all,  and  a  consequent  relapse  to  the  level  of  the  pri- 
mary Instincts,  neglects  the  fundamental  nature  of  the 
evolutionary  process.  Environment  is  not  merely  the 
mechanical  and  stereotyped  part  of  nature,  but  first  of 
all  man,  and  in  man  the  evolutionary  process  so  far  from 
having  stopped  is  going  on  with  even  more  rapidity  as  it 
becomes  more  complex.  Our  environment  never  was  more 
in  the  making  than  now  and  never  furnished  as  large  or 
rapidly  shifting  a  scale  of  selective  values.  If  the  old 
men  just  now  are  in  danger  of  being  shelved,  as  is  often 
complained,  it  is  not  so  much  because  they  are  old  as  that 
they  grow  stereotyped  and  cannot  keep  up  with  the  rapid 
rearrangements.  The  young  old  men,  the  geniuses  of  the 
race,  were  never  more  valued. 

What  the  social  environment  does,  then,  as  embodied  in 
human  behavior  and  in  the  products  of  mind,  is  to  furnish 
ever  new  stimuli  and  more  complex  survival  conditions. 
What  the  individual  must  do  to  respond  to  the  fullest  ex- 
tent is  to  meet  the  new  demands  with  the  corresponding 
variations.  Fortunately  it  is  not  necessary  to  respond  to 
more  than  a  small  number  of  the  physico-social  character- 
istics in  order  to  survive.  Only  an  absolute  being  could  be 
equipped  to  respond  to  the  universe,  point  for  point.  A 


40  Truth  and  Reality 

man  may  reach  the  highest  eminence  of  social  usefulness 
by  the  narrowness  of  his  specialty,  if  for  the  rest  he  con- 
form to  certain  general  survival  tendencies  such  as  honesty 
and  truthfulness  (and  I  regret  to  say  that  does  not  always 
seem  necessary  at  present).  Thus  he  may  rise  to  the  high- 
est efficiency  in  the  business  world  without  responding 
to  things  philosophical,  artistic  or  even  religious.  A 
genius  is  one  who  is  gifted  with  an  unusual  variation,  either 
in  the  direction  of  that  which  has  no  direct  survival  value 
but  calls  off  the  play  tendencies  of  man,  such  as  art,  or  in 
the  direction  of  greater  survival  advantage,  as  in  the  case 
of  the  moral  prophets  or  the  inventors  of  tools.  Nothing 
is  more  obvious  than  the  marked  difference  in  the  range  as 
well  as  quality  of  response  in  different  individuals.  Some 
brains,  as  those  of  the  idiot,  are  remarkably  opaque;  others, 
like  those  of  the  genius,  show  a  wonderful  power  of  refract- 
ing light  in  brilliant  and  unusual  ways ;  but  each  mind  re- 
flects the  light  by  virtue  of  its  own  constitution  as  manifest 
in  each  stage  of  the  series. 

We  get  as  much  value  and  significance  out  of  nature  and 
institutional  life  as  we  have  corresponding  tendencies.  To 
the  man  who  lacks  the  play  of  esthetic  tendency  and  who 
is  preoccupied  with  the  primary  and  secondary  instincts 
"sunset  and  evening  star"  are  nothing,  except  perhaps  a 
weather  sign.  In  the  words  of  Coleridge, 

O  Lady,  we  receive  but  what  we  give, 
And  in  our  life  alone  does  nature  live. 

And  so  with  the  institutional  equipment  of  the  race.  Our 
religious  tendencies  determine  our  religion,  not  the  oppo- 
site. If  we  lack  the  feeling  toward  the  supernatural  and 
the  sense  of  dependence,  religion  is  not  for  us.  If  we  are 
lacking  again  in  esthetic  appreciation,  it  is  very  natural  that 


Mind  as  Instinct  41 

we  should  deem  art  useless  or  worse  and  proceed  to  make 
bare  the  temples,  or  even  destroy  them  as  some  would-be 
reformers  did.  As  the  difference  in  creeds  and  the  dread 
of  hell  disappear,  religious  denominations  will  separate  in 
their  worship  on  the  ground  of  the  real  psychic  prefer- 
ences of  individuals  as  regards  the  emphasis  of  the  ethical, 
the  mystical,  the  esthetic  or  the  philosophical  tendencies 
—  always  with  the  possibility  of  course  that  the  more 
primary  tendencies  of  custom  and  loyalty  may  keep  a  man 
where  he  does  not  psychologically  belong.  Institutions 

& 

are  created  by  our  tendencies,  and  they  are  properly  selec- 
tive of  us  only  as  they  make  tendencies  go  off  in  us; 
though  if  they  fail  to  select,  they  may  eliminate  and  so 
produce  artificial  uniformity. 

That  is  as  true  of  the  state  and  family  as  of  religion. 
The  fundamental  virtues  which  underlie  social  life,  such 
as  honesty,  truthfulness  and  kindness,  cannot  be  produced 
in  people.  The  exciting  of  other  tendencies,  such  as  fear 
and  gain,  may  produce  counterfeit  reactions  for  those  men- 
tioned above,  inhibiting  the  original  tendencies.  And  some 
people  live  a  respectable  life  that  way,  no  doubt.  But  it  is 
a  great  mistake  to  suppose  that  because  the  child  at  one 
stage  of  its  development  reacts  largely  on  the  basis  of  the 
primary  instincts  and  shows  no  sense  of  truth,  or  honesty, 
or  kindness,  or  beauty,  that,  therefore,  these  tendencies  are 
produced  at  a  later  period.  They  are  acquired  no  more 
than  love  is  acquired  as  the  nervous  system  matures,  though 
an  awkward  regime  of  stimuli  may  indeed  fail  to  set  them 
off.  Our  bias  for  landscape  painting  instead  of  character 
sketches;  Ingersoll's  fondness  for  the  babble  of  the  brook 
and  fear  of  Niagara ;  our  preference  for  the  cathedral  to 
the  Quaker  meeting  house,  in  so  far  as  preference  is  active ; 


42  Truth  and  Reality 

our  enjoyment  of  lyric  sweetness  rather  than  the  searching 
of  tragedy,  —  all  these  preferences  are  conditions  or  presup- 
positions of  our  experience ;  and  while  they  may  be  vio- 
lated or  forced  by  the  environment,  cannot  be  produced 
by  it. 

Thus  dies  the  old  controversy  of  empiricism  vs.  in- 
nate ideas.  But  not  without  each  side  having  contributed 
its  immortal  say.  It  was  a  beautiful  figure  of  Plato — that 
of  recollection  from  a  previous  existence.  In  the  process 
of  experience,  especially  that  of  dialectic  cross-examina- 
tion, the  soul  becomes  conscious  of  its  past,  of  the  results 
of  previous  existences.  Especially  are  our  ideals,  which 
we  bring  to  bear  upon  experience,  the  echoes  of  this  long 
history.  The  fundamental  truth  remains,  though  we  have 
changed  our  terminology  and  substituted  race  history  for 
the  dim  preexistence  of  the  individual  soul  and  biological 
tendency  for  dormant  Ideas  —  not  because  we  are  wiser, 
but  because  it  is  more  convenient.  All  other  theories  of 
innate  ideas  are  but  the  reverberations  of  Plato.  And  with 
them  all  we  must  agree  that,  unless  the  individual  brought 
a  constitution  to  experience,  it  would  be  but  a  squashy, 
unorganized  affair.  With  the  empiricists,  on  the  other 
hand,  we  must  own  that  the  content  of  experience,  the 
definiteness  and  meaning  of  instinct,  can  only  come  as  the 
individual  strives  to  meet  the  specific  situations  of  the 
environment.  There  are  no  innate  ideas.  It  is  the  form 
of  experience  which  is  predetermined.  The  genetic  story 
of  this  connective  tissue  we  shall  try  to  tell  in  the  next 
chapter.1 

1 1  take  pleasure  in  acknowledging  my  indebtedness  to  other  workers  in 
this  field,  especially  Principal  C.  Lloyd  Morgan  and  Professor  James  Mark 
Baldwin,  who  by  their  splendid  works  have  directed  me  into  this  field  of 
thought. 


CHAPTER   III 

THE  CATEGORIES  OF  INTELLIGENCE 

IN   examining  the  categories  of   intelligence,  we  shall 
«..  adopt  the  genetic  method.     We  shall  try  to  ascertain  what 
i^the  presuppositions  of  experience  are  at  each  stage  of  de- 
„  -.  'Velopment.     In  this  attempt,  Kant  must  be  recognized  as 

v.  our  great  precursor.1     Indeed,  the  "  Critique  of  Pure  Rea-      p| 
jLfSon  "  is  a  great  work,  viewed  as  genetic  psychology.     We 

J**^  ^rf 

cannot,  however,  any  longer  use  the  term  reason  to  include 
the  whole  range  of  intellectual  development.     We   shall 
therefore  substitute  the  term  intelligence,  which  means  ca- 
^pacity  to  learn  from  experience.     We  must  also,  in  order  to 
get  Kant's  real  working  categories,  ignore  the  curiously 
tacked-on  tables  of  formal   logic,  and   take   his  working 
^"categories   as   they   appear  in  the  body   of  the  Critique. 
*  ^Finally,  while  in  any  such  effort  as  this  we  must  own  our 


*- 

• 


I 


i 


Indebtedness  to  Kant,  we  must  not  forget  to  recognize  the 
splendid  work  done  by  recent  genetic  psychology. 

In  order  to  discuss  the  categories  of  intelligence,   we 
Tmust   recognize  the  various  levels  of  intellectual  develop- 
>ment.     And  while  our  nomenclature  must  be  different,  and 
>ur  treatment  still  more  different,  these  levels  coincide,  as 
matter  of  fact,  with  those  of  Kant's  great  work. 
We  must  also  recognize  at  the  outset  the  conative  char- 
cter  of  intelligence,  so  admirably  brought  out  by  Professor 

*p     l  That  Kant  was  a  thorough  evolutionist,  not  only  in  his  theory  of  the 
• »  stellar  world,  but  also  as  regards  the  development  of  life  and  thought,  has 
been  shown  by  Dr.  Paul  Carus  in  his  volume,  •'  Kant  and  Spencer." 


44  Truth  and  Reality 

Stout.  Life  is  fundamentally  impulsive.  It  consists  of 
certain  tendencies,  which  strive  for  fulfillment.  It  is  the 
nature  of  impulse  to  persist  with  varied  effort,  until  the 
tendency  is  realized.  The  complexity  of  impulse,  and  the 
efficiency  of  the  adaptation  to  the  varying  conditions  which 
it  must  meet,  grow  very  much  greater  with  the  increase  in 
the  complexity  of  intelligence.  But  throughout  this  devel- 
opment, the  same  fundamental  impulsive  character  persists. 
And  intelligence  remains  an  instrument,  however  elaborate, 
for  fulfilling  the  demands  of  the  will,  its  need  for  work  and 
for  play. 

I.    The  Perceptual  Level  of  Intelligence 

On  the  perceptual  level  of  intelligence  even,  we  must 
recognize  certain  biological  presuppositions  as  fundamental. 
First  of  all,  Kant  is  right  that  we  presuppose  certain  space 
coordinations,  which  are  not  derived  from  external  experi- 
ence. This  does  not  mean  that  we  can  take  for  granted 
the  postulates  of  Euclidean  geometry.  But  it  seems  clear 
now  that  we  do  not  learn  our  space  reactions  by  making  a 
map,  visual  or  tactual,  before  making  the  reactions.  On 
the  contrary,  we  inherit  certain  tendencies  to  reaction 
which  are  brought  into  play  by  the  stimuli  of  the  organism ; 
and  by  continuous  trials  and  the  elimination  of  unsuccessful 
movements,  these  reactions  become  definite.  The  child 
responds  to  the  rhythms  of  music  with  certain  rhythmic 
movements  of  its  own  not  because  it  has  previously  learned 
those  movements ;  but  because  it  is  biologically  so  consti- 
tuted that  it  cannot  help  responding,  any  more  than  a  kitten 
can  help  running  after  the  moving  string.  To  show  how 
largely  the  coordinations  are  biological,  I  will  quote  from 


TJie  Categories  of  Intelligence  45 

C.  Lloyd  Morgan  : *  "  I  took  a  young  pheasant,  which  had 
been  hatched  sometime  in  the  night,  from  the  incubator 
drawer  at  nine  o'clock  in  the  morning.  He  was  very  un- 
steady on  his  legs,  so  I  held  him  in  my  hands  and  tried  to 
induce  him  to  peck  at  a  piece  of  egg  yolk,  held  in  a  pair 
of  forceps.  He  did  not  do  so,  but  he  followed,  with  his 
head,  every  movement  of  the  object  in  a  narrow  circle 
about  two  inches  in  front  of  his  beak.  Simple  as  the  action 
seems,  it  shows  a  striking  example  of  congenital,  coordi- 
nated movements  accurately  related  to  movement  in  the 
visual' field,  the  whole  performed  without  any  possibility 
of  learning  or  practice  and  in  less  than  half  an  hour  after 
the  bird  had  first  seen  the  light." 

In  human  development,  these  spatial  coordinations  are 
of  course  very  imperfect  at  birth,  but  even  so  it  is  true  that 
the  responses  are  the  results  of  the  growth  series  of  the 
organism  which  is  made  definite  in  the  try-out  in  connection 
with  the  actual  situations.  Even  the  presuppositions  which 
lie  at  the  basis  of  geometry  may  be  said  to  be  implied  in 
this  biological  constitution  of  perceptual  experience.  The 
straight  line  is  not  a  generalization  from  cases  of  experience, 
but  is  a  presupposition  which  the  organism  brings  with  it 
to  its  consciously  constructed  efforts  and  which  must  there- 
fore be  part  of  the  organic  tendencies  of  the  individual, 
rather  than  be  credited  to  the  learning  process. 

If  it  is  true  that  we  bring  a  certain  organization  to  ex- 
perience, even  on  the  lowest  level,  as  regards  space  co- 
ordination, it  is  likewise  true  that  we  must  bring  an  original 
adjustment  as  regards  the  sense  of  time.  We  do  not  learn 
the  sense  of  duration,  any  more  than  we  learn  the  funda- 
mental space  adjustments.  The  question  may  well  be 

1  Stout,  "  Manual  of  Psychology,"  p.  253. 


46  Truth  and  Reality 

raised,  whether  we  can  have  a  sense  of  time  before  we 
have  memory.  It  is  probably  true  that  we  cannot  have  a 
definite  consciousness  of  before  and  after,  before  we  have 
the  passing  series  of  ideas. 

But  the  conditions  for  a  consciousness  of  duration  cer- 
tainly exist  before  we  have  memory.  Of  this  we  have  some 
intimation  in  our  own  experience.  We  may  have  a  cumu- 
lative sense  of  meaning  without  reference  to  ideas,  as  in 
the  consciousness  of  the  continuity  of  a  melody.  Unless 
the  earlier  tone  sensations  actually  persisted  in  conscious- 
ness, we  could  not  have  the  cumulative  realization  of  a 
melody,  of  a  tonal  whole.  In  pathological  cases  we  can  find 
numerous  illustrations  of  a  consciousness  of  time,  without 
ideas  being  present.  In  my  own  awakening  from  a  light- 
ning stroke,  I  had  a  consciousness  of  the  time  elapsed  dur- 
ing the  vague  perceptual  state  as  soon  as  I  began  to 
realize  the  situation,  even  though  I  had  had  no  ideas  in  the 
meantime.  In  awakening  from  seemingly  dreamless  sleep, 
we  have  a  consciousness  of  an  interval  having  elapsed,  and 
with  some  training  the  organism  seems  to  be  able  to  keep 
accurate  account  of  time,  without  reference  to  intervening 
ideational  experience. 


Not  only  do  we  have  a  basis  for  the  consciousness  of 
duration,  but  we  have  also  a  provision  for  the  measure  of 
duration  on  the  perceptual  level.  Some  of  our  impulses  are 
of  a  rhythmic  character.  Such  is,  for  example,  the  impulse 
for  food.  We  can  see,  therefore,  how  such  impulses  can 
divide  the  life  of  perception  into  certain  fairly  definite 
longer  periods,  not  to  mention  the  shorter  periods  marked 
by  the  organic  rhythms  against  the  perceptual  background. 
So  that  we  have  present,  not  only  a  sense  of  duration,  but 
certain  time  wholes,  such  as  we  can  best  realize  perhaps 


The  Categories  of  Intelligence  47 

by  comparison  with  our  esthetic  time  wholes  in  the  case  of 
music. 

While  we  recognize  the  sense  of  time  as  a  fundamental 
category  of  experience,  we  must  not,  of  course,  suppose  that 
our  modern  chronological  measurements,  any  more  than 
our  Euclidean  Geometry,  is  part  of  the  original  equipment 
of  the  organism.  What  the  organism  possesses  is  a  certain 
time  orientation,  as  it  possesses  a  certain  space  orientation, 
which  is  made  definite  in  the  course  of  experience. 

We  have  recognized  so  far  two  categories  on  the  per- 
ceptuarievel.  We  must  add  a  third,  namely,  habit.  The 
organism  is  so  constituted  that  even  on  the  perceptual 
level  it  can  profit  by  experience.  Learning  by  habit  is  a 
very  much  slower  process  than  learning  by  means  of 
ideas.  But  it  is  also  a  much  surer  process.  We  are 
familiar  with  the  importance  of  habit  in  our  own  expe- 
rience. In  order  to  acquire  any  delicate  adjustments  on 
the  part  of  the  organism,  we  must  try  over  and  over  again, 
the  futile  efforts  being  passed  over,  the  more  successful 
efforts  being  emphasized  by  attention,  until  finally  the 
accurate  movements  become  part  of  our  nervous  equip- 
ment. This  can  be  illustrated  in  any  game  of  skill,  as  in 
playing  tennis.  The  lower  animals,  even  the  unicellular 
organisms,  we  now  know,  are  capable  of  profiting  by  repe- 
tition, in  fixing  certain  useful  adaptations  in  the  way  of 
conduct.  The  curve  of  habit  is  a  gradual  one,  fewer  unsuc- 
cessful efforts  appearing  in  the  course  of  repetition,  but 
with  no  sharp  break  in  the  process  such  as  we  find  when 
the  action  is  pictured  in  a  memory  idea.  When  a  horse 
wants  to  stop  at  a  place  where  he  has  stopped  once  before 
or  returns  by  the  same  road  he  has  only  once  gone,  that  is 
associative  memory  and  not  habit. 


48  Truth  and  Reality 

Another  category  which  we  must  recognize  on  the  per- 
ceptual level  is  that  of  imitation,  or  the  tendency  of  the 
organism  to  repeat  the  conduct  of  its  environment.  The 
importance  of  this  tendency  in  the  learning  process  of 
the  lower  animals  cannot  be  overemphasized.  A  large 
amount  of  the  adjustment,  which  in  the  past  has  been 
credited  to  instinct,  must  now  be  credited  to  tradition  and 
imitation.  In  this  way,  a  young  animal  learns  to  profit  by 
the  hard-earned  experience  of  its  predecessors  and  thus  to 
make  its  indefinite  instincts  more  adapted  to  the  specific 
demands  of  the  environment.  In  a  similarly  imitative 
manner  the  child  comes  to  master  the  mechanism  of 
language,  and  thus  to  prepare  itself  for  the  functions  of 
the  higher  stages  of  mental  development.  A  child  does 
not  have  an  idea  of  language  first,  or  a  picture  of  the 
movements  which  it  is  going  to  make ;  given  such  stimuli, 
it  cannot  help  responding,  or  attempting  to  respond,  in 
such  a  way. 

2.    The  Level  of  Reproductive  Imagination 

On  the  level  of  reproductive  imagination  we  recognize  a 
still  greater  economy  in  the  way  of  procedure.  We  have 
seen  that  habit  is  at  best  a  slow  and  stereotyped  process 
of  adjustment.  A  memory  image  which  furnishes  at  one 
stroke  a  picture  of  the  concrete  situation  and  its  adjust- 
ment is  a  short  cut  compared  to  habit.  The  image  may  be 
compared,  as  Bergson  says,  to  the  cinematograph  copy. 
It  records,  in  a  simultaneous  picture,  the  successive  acts  of 
attention  which  were  involved  in  the  original  adjustment, 
leaving  out  such  details  as  were  irrelevant  to  attention  and 
being  therefore  more  sketchy  than  the  perceptual  situa- 
tion. 


The  Categories  of  Intelligence  49 

The  moving  pictures  of  the  reproductive  imagination 
presuppose  certain  tendencies  or  laws  which  are  part  of 
our  mental  constitution  and  are  not  learned  by  experience. 
They  may  therefore,  in  Kantian  phrase,  be  termed  a  priori. 
We  must  recognize  three  categories  of  reproductive  imagi- 
nation ;  namely,  contiguity,  similarity  and  set. 

When  we  attend  to  various  items  of  experience  as  part 
of  one  space  and  time  setting,  they  come  to  form  one  con- 
text or  part  of  one  disposition,  in  such  a  manner  that  after- 
wards, when  one  item  is  brought  into  play,  it  will  tend  to 
reinstate  the  other  items  also.  What  particular  item  shall 
be  brought  up  at  any  one  time,  other  things  being  the 
same,  will,  of  course,  depend  upon  the  strength  of  the 
habit,  which,  in  turn,  is  conditioned  by  the  number  of 
repetitions,  or  by  the  vividness  of  any  one  excitement,  or  by 
the  recency  of  the  occurrence.  The  events  of  our  mental 
life,  inasmuch  as  they  must  run  through  attention,  will  be 
found  to  be  strung  upon  this  law  of  contiguity  of  interest. 

The  law  of  contiguity,  however,  is  not  the  only  method 
by  means  of  which  the  facts  are  strung  in  our  mental 
life.  There  is  also  a  tendency  to  pass  from  one  fact  to 
another  and  to  string  them  together  in  new  ways  by  reason 
of  similars,  whether  the  similarity  be  one  of  quality,  or  rela- 
tion, or  an  identical  word.  Take  a  case  of  blue  sky  sug- 
gesting the  blue  sea.  We  are  taking  for  granted  here  that 
the  two  have  not  been  experienced  together,  for  then  it 
would  only  be  a  case  of  contiguity.  When  blue  sky,  how- 
ever, suggests  blue  sea  without  their  being  part  of  a  previ- 
ous context  of  interest,  we  have  a  new  pivot  for  recall. 
What  happens  in  this  case  ?  Not  habit,  because  there  has 
been  no  habit  as  between  these  processes.  The  attention 
to  the  identity  of  the  blue  quality  becomes  a  new  linkage. 


5O  Truth  and  Reality 

A  new  connection  has  thus  arisen  as  a  result  of  conscious- 
ness, which  affords  a  bond  not  made  before.  This  con- 
sciousness of  a  part  belonging  to  two  contexts  by  virtue  of 
the  identity  of  some  elements  within  them  is  entirely  dif- 
ferent from  the  contiguity  relation.  There  is  no  contiguity 
until  after  attention  has  made  the  identification,  after  the 
connection  has  once  been  made;  that  is,  after  the  fact. 

In  order  to  understand  either  the  operation  by  contiguity 
or  by  similarity,  it  is  necessary  to  add  another  category, 
that  of  set.  As  a  matter  of  fact  neither  contiguity  nor  sim- 
ilarity operates  mechanically.  They  are  steered  in  either 
case  by  the  dominant  interest  or  total  impulse  at  the  time. 
The  mind  operates  somewhat  like  the  switch  system  of  a 
railway.  When  one  switch  is  open,  as  the  result  of  inter- 
est, the  other  switches  will  tend,  more  or  less,  to  be  closed, 
though  in  the  case  of  some  minds  it  seems  to  be  a  case  of 
continual  running  off  into  the  other  directions,  and  run- 
ning back  again.  The  total  train  of  association,  however, 
is  dominated  by  this  selective  disposition  of  which  I  have 
spoken  as  set.  Take  it  in  the  case  of  contiguity :  while 
many  facts  have  been  attended  to  together,  and  even 
though  the  mechanical  habit  should  be  as  favorable  in  one 
direction  as  in  the  other,  the  tendency  will  be  to  run  the 
train  of  associations  in  accordance  with  the  interest  or 
affective  tone  at  the  time. 

In  recall  by  similars,  the  category  of  set  becomes  still 
more  obvious.  The  old  contiguities  are  traversed  in  all 
sorts  of  new  ways,  because  of  the  dominant  disposition  at 
the  time.  The  set  may  be  a  practical  end  to  be  accom- 
plished, a  certain  emotional  tone  at  the  time  or  a  fascinat- 
ing image  which  for  the  time  being  holds  the  field.  But 
in  any  case  the  mind  does  not  act  merely  from  part  to 


The  Categories  of  Intelligence  5 1 

part,  but  the  preceding  events  and  the  present  context  of 
association  and  emotion  must  be  taken  into  account  in  un- 
derstanding the  course  of  ideas.  In  reproductive  imagina- 
tion this  interest  is  impulsive  and  emotional,  is  not  organized, 
and  soon  spends  itself,  and  gives  place  to  another  impulse 
or  emotion.  Hence  the  constellations  of  ideas  which  hang 
together  by  means  of  these  individual  impulses  form  largely 
independent  clusters,  except  as  shot  through  now  and  then 
by  the  consciousness  of  similars.  It  is  not  until  the  reflec- 
tive level,  however,  that  we  have  an  indefinitely  sustained 

& 

set  or  organized  interest. 

3.    The  Level  of  Empirical  Generalization 

If  the  memory  image  is  an  economic  device  in  the  ad- 
justment of  the  organism,  a  still  greater  economy  is  effected 
when  we  come  to  the  level  of  thought.  By  means  of  rea- 
soning we  can  free  ourselves  from  the  slavery  to  the  con- 
crete situation,  by  substituting  for  the  total  situation  certain 
characters  or  relations  which  are  significant  for  the  type  of 
adjustment  in  question.  Thus  we  can,  not  merely  repeat 
adjustments  once  gone  through  as  in  the  case  of  memory, 
but  meet  new  situations  on  the  basis  of  the  characteristic 
identities  which  we  have  abstracted  from  experience.  On 
this  level  of  generalization,  we  must  take  account  of  four 
different  categories  or  forms  of  synthesis.  There  is  the 
synthesis  of  quantity,  the  synthesis  of  quality,  the  synthesis 
of  cause  and  effect  and  the  synthesis  of  individual  inter- 
penetration  or  substance. 

Let  us  speak  first  of  the  synthesis  of  quantity.  Experi- 
ence is  such  that  we  can  recognize  the  characteristic  of 
more  or  less  in  comparing  its  processes.  On  the  basis  of 
this  distinction  we  can  apply  our  conventional  units  to  our 


52  Truth  and  Reality 

space,  time  and  energetic  relations,  and  spread  our  facts 
out  into  series.  It  is  unnecessary  to  say  that  the  category 
of  quantity  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  classification  of 
propositions  in  formal  logic,  though  the  identity  of  the 
word  in  the  two  cases  seems  to  have  confused  Kant.1 
Nor  can  we  agree  with  Kant  that  quantity,  as  we  take  it 
in  experience,  is  an  aggregate  of  previously  given  parts.2 
We  do  not  synthesize  an  infinite  number  of  positions  in  the 
drawing  of  the  line.  As  a  matter  of  fact  we  would  have 
to  synthesize  infinities  of  an  infinite  number  of  Machtig- 
keiten.  And  then  we  would  miss  the  real  character  which 
makes  quantity  continuous.  Infinite  divisibility  is  a  purely 
conceptual  and  hypothetical  affair.  We  do  not  make  any 
such  synthesis  psychologically. 

Once  having  arrived  at  a  unit  of  measure  we  have  a  great 
advantage  in  the  description  of  the  world  of  processes. 
We  can  take  facts  over  again  and  compare  them ;  we  can 
make  our  own  conduct  definite  with  reference  to  them 
on  the  basis  of  this  quantitative  spreading  out  of  facts  of 
experience.  With  such  accuracy  of  description  we  have 
the  advent  of  science.  And  all  the  facts  of  experience  lend 
themselves  to  this  quantitative  way  of  taking  them.  They 
are  capable  of  being  taken  as  more  or  less,  if  not  exten- 
sively, at  least  intensively.  * 

Besides  spreading  the  facts  out  into  quantitative  series, 
we  can  spread  them  out  on  the  basis  of  their  degree  of 
difference  as  regards  their  qualities.  Thus  we  spread  out 
our  color  series,  our  tonal  series,  our  number  series,  etc. 
The  number  series,  which  must  be  taken  fundamentally  as 


The  Categories  of  Intelligence  53 

an  order  series,  is  the  most  important  of  all,  as  it  furnishes 
the  hierarchy  of  values  which  we  must  presuppose  in  all  of 
our  measurements.  It  is  not  true  that  quantitative  com- 
parison is  more  fundamental  than  qualitative.  Difference 
in  qualities  is  just  as  important  in  the  adjustment  of  the 
organism  as  the  consciousness  of  more  or  less.  And 
spreading  tones  out  into  series  of  octaves  and  colors  into 
their  respective  color  dimensions  cannot  be  reduced  to 
quantitative  comparison,  whether  intensive  or  extensive. 
Nor  can  we  make  quantity  a  mere  result  of  quality.  Facts 
can  be  taken  as  more  or  less  in  experience,  as  differing  in 
extensity  or  at  least  in  intensity,  independently  of  variation 
of  quality.  We  cannot,  finally,  regard  qualities  as  varying 
in  infinitesimal  degrees  to  zero,  as  Kant  supposes.1  Such 
variation  is  a  purely  conceptual  affair.  Perceptual  qualities 
have  a  finite  threshold  and  vary  by  finite  increments, 
whether  intensively  or  in  kind.  ^ 

Another  method  of  synthesis  is  that  of  causality.  It 
was  Hume  that  showed  that  when  facts  follow  each  other 
according  to  invariable  antecedents  and  consequents,  we 
come  to  regard  them  as  causally  connected ;  in  fact,  cause 
and  effect  merely  mean  that  facts  are  definitely  predictable 
under  certain  conditions.  There  is  nothing  hidden  or 
mysterious  about  causality.  The  constraint,  however,  can- 
not lie  merely  in  subjective  habit  or  even  in  a  category  of 
causality.  The  constraint  must  lie  finally  in  the  processes 
of  which  we  take  account  The  necessity  which  we  feel  in 
regard  to  certain  sequences  is  in  part  due  to  mental  consti- 
tution, to  be  sure,  but  on  the  one  hand,  it  could  only  be 
evoked  by  the  conditions  of  antecedents  and  consequents 
on  the  part  of  the  content ;  on  the  other,  the  necessity  of 
1  Op.  dt.,  p.  138. 


54  Truth  and  Reality 

the  content  relation  must  prove  itself  independent  of  the 
subjective  feeling.  The  latter  has  often  attached  itself  to 
the  wrong  content  and  must  be  corrected  in  the  course  of 
experience.  The  method  of  agreement,  therefore,  must  be 
supplemented  by  the  method  of  difference  in  some  form. 
Kant  himself  recognized  that  the  particular  causal  series 
must  be  ascertained  from  experience  and  cannot  be  read 
off  a  priori. 

We  cannot  recognize  reciprocity  as  a  distinct  category, 
on  the  same  level  as  causality,  as  Kant  does.  Reciprocity 
is  merely  causality  read  both  ways.  It  is  double  causality. 
The  best  illustration  is  that  of  gravity,  where  one  mass  does 
not  merely  pull  the  other,  but  each  body  responds  to  gravi- 
tational influence  according  to  the  mass  and  inversely  as 
the  square  of  the  distance.  The  same  would  be  true  of 
any  other  causal  relation.  Each  factor  in  the  causal  rela- 
tion contributes  to  the  result.  Reciprocity  is  merely  testi- 
mony to  the  fact  that  the  universe  has  a  plural  character  — 
consists  of  many  centers  of  energy.  If  such  were  not  the 
case,  there  .would  be  no  causality  at  all.  Causality  in  a 

. '  •  -  <•  % , ,          .    .~       J 

monistic  world  has  no  significance. 

Finally,  a  fourth  method  of  synthesis  is  that  of  individual 
interpenetration.  In  the  case  of  causality,  the  characteris- 
tics appear  in  a  sequence,  according  to  the  successive  condi- 
tions which  set  them  off.  In  the  category  of  substance  or 
individuality,  the  characteristics  must  be  conceived  as  co- 
existing and  interpenetrating.  They  exist  in  the  service  of 
one  impulse  or  end.  Whether  different  characters  can  so 
interpenetrate  we  cannot  here  argue.  We  must  merely 
insist  that  if  they  do  so  coexist,  if  they  must  be  taken  in 
such  a  manner  in  the  procedure  of  experience,  then  they 
can  coexist  and  interpenetrate. 


The  Categories  of  Intelligence  55 

Individual  synthesis  takes  two  forms  in  the  procedure  of 
experience.  We  distinguish  between  individual  things  and 
individual  selves.  Individual  things  are  such  as  they  must 
be  taken  in  their  external  relations.  They  have  no  inward- 
ness of  meaning  and  value.  Individual  selves  must  be 
recognized  as  having  a  meaning  of  their  own.  But  the 
method  of  synthesis  is  the  same  in  either  case.  In  either 
case  we  have  the  interpenetration  of  qualities.  In  either 
case  the  diversity  of  characters  is  unified  by  its  being 
taken  as  expressing  one  impulse  or  fulfilling  one  purpose. 

& 

4.    The  Level  of  Idealization 

In  the  first  place,  it  may  be  well  to  define  what  we 
understand  by  ideal  synthesis.  We  can  do  no  better  than 
to  state  the  admirable  definition  of  Baldwin  :  "  Ideals  are 
the  forms  which  we  feel  our  conceptions  would  take  if  we 
were  able  to  realize  in  them  a  satisfying  degree  of  unity, 
harmony,  significance  and  universality."  1  Four  characters 
are  involved  in  ideal  synthesis.  First  we  demand  a  unity 
of  parts  within  a  whole.  This  means  that  the  various  facts 
must  be  capable  of  being  understood  as  expressing  one 
idea.  In  the  second  place,  there  must  be  harmony  ;  that 
is,  the  parts  within  the  whole  must  be  seen  to  support  or 
reenforce  each  other.  Thirdly,  there  must  be  clearness 
and  distinctness  or  simplicity  of  relationships.  That  is, 
we  must  be  able  to  pass  with  ease  or  fluency  from  one 
point  to  another.  And  fourthly,  the  ideal  synthesis  must 
be  capable  of  social  sharing  or  universality.  We  cannot 
here  follow  these  requirements  for  each  field  of  ideal  syn- 
thesis, such  as  the  esthetic,  ethical,  etc.  Each  field  is  limited 

1  Baldwin,  "Feeling  and  Will,"  p.  202. 


+  « 


56  Truth  and  Reality 

by  its  own  content  and  its  peculiar  constitution,  whether 
it  be  the  satisfaction  of  the  requirements  of  the  intellect, 
or  the  requirements  of  feeling  in  its  specific  forms  of 
realization,  or  the  requirements  of  the  will  in  its  moral 
endeavor,  or  the  requirements  which  our  total  nature  sets 
for  the  unification  and  conservation  of  values.  But  here 
our  concern  is  with  the  ideal  of  intelligence  alone.  Can 
the  universe  of  facts  with  which  intelligence  deals  be  said 
to  possess  these  characteristics,  so  far  as  knowledge  is  con- 
cerned ?  We  cannot  say  as  yet.  For  us,  as  finites,  a  com- 
plete knowledge  is  an  ideal.  In  the  meantime,  we  must 
live  by  faith.  But  if  we  did  possess  such  a  knowledge, 
the  ideal  would  require  that  it  possess  unity  of  principle, 
that  is,  the  facts  would  be  seen  to  follow  according  to  a 
certain  identity  which  could  be  described.  There  must 
further  be  harmony,  or  mutual  support  of  parts.  Facts 
would  lean  on  ideas,  and  ideas  on  facts,  without  break  in 
the  adjustment  or  the  transitions.  The  relations  would 
further  be  seen  to  be  clear  and  distinct ;  that  is,  every  fact 
would  be  definable  by  means  of  a  few  finite  principles. 
And  such  a  synthesis  would  finally  be  universal ;  that  is, 
it  would  everywhere  compel  the  social  agreement  of  all 
rational  beings.  While  such  an  ideal  synthesis  lies  beyond 
our  experience,  we  cannot  say  it  is  impossible.  On  the 
contrary,  we  must  have  explicit  faith  in  its  realization.  It 
is  the  passion  for  such  unity  which  furnishes  the  real  motive 
of  all  ef  our  scientific  endeavor.  In  the  meantime  we  can 
work  for  it  and  approximate  to  it.  With  Kant  we  would 
agree,  "  These  ideals,  though  they  cannot  claim  objective 
reality  (existence),  are  not  therefore  to  be  considered  as 
mere  chimeras,  but  supply  reason  with  an  indispensable 
standard,  because  it  requires  the  concept  of  that  which  is 


The  Categories  of  Intelligence  57 

perfect  of  its  kind,  in  order  to  estimate  and  measure  by  it 
the  degrees  and  the  number  of  the  defects  in  the  imperfect 
.  .  .  This  is  the  case  with  the  ideal  of  reason,  which  must 
always  rest  on  definite  concepts,  and  serve  as  a  rule  and 
model  whether  for  imitation  or  criticism." * 

What  the  ideal  of  reason  or  the  philosophic  conscious- 
ness adds  to  our  scientific  work  of  generalization  is  a  feel- 
ing for  wholeness  within  the  fragmentary  generalizations 
of  our  experience.  This  is  more  or  less  implicitly  present 
in  all  our  sorting  of  experience,  even  if  not  brought  into 
definite'consciousness.  It  always  sets  the  implied  goal  of 
our  endeavor.  Now  this  feeling  for  wholeness  takes  a 
fourfold  form  as  expressed  in  terms  of  the  content  of  our 
expeTience.  It  becomes  the  demand  for  the  unity  of  our 
inner  experience  or  the  ego ;  the  demand  for  the  unity  of 
our  outer  experience  or  nature ;  the  demand  for  the  unity 
of  our  social  experience,  our  fellow  world,  or  history;  and 
finally,  the  demand  for  unity  in  the  totality  of  being  or  the 
absolute. 

In  the  case  of  these  ideal  wholes,  we  must  recognize 
with  Kant  that  they  have  no  relevance  except  as  applied 
to  reality  as  experienced.  They  are  tendencies  or  demands 
on  the  part  of  our  mental  constitution,  in  dealing  with  its 
objects.  Kant  is  right,  too,  as  regards  the  human  charac- 
ter of  this  conceptual  construction.  We  cannot  say  that 
there  are  not  beings  in  the  universe  differently  organized 
from  ourselves,  for  which  such  ideals  would  have  no  rele- 
vance. In  fact,  we  are  pretty  certain  that  such  ideals  are 
not  present  in  animals  limited  to  the  planes  of  perception 
and  reproductive  imagination.  Whether,  however,  as  Kant 
suggests,  there  are  beings  superior  to  ourselves,  that  have 

1  Max  Muller's  translation  of  the  "Critique  of  Pure  Reason,"  p.  461. 


58  Truth  and  Reality 

a  higher  mode  of  intuition,  lying  outside  our  methods  of 
synthesis,  it  is  idle  to  inquire.  We,  at  any  rate,  must  deal 
with  truth  as  the  goal  of  the  realization  of  such  capacities 
as  we  have  as  human.  We  must  part  company  with  Kant 
when  he  assumes  that  reality  by  being  experienced  is 
thereby  "faked,"  subjectively  encrusted,  in  such  a  way 
that  we  are  prevented  from  knowing  things  as  they  are. 
We  must,  on  the  contrary,  believe  that  reality  is  more  of  the 
same  kind  of  thing  which  we  are  grasping  in  a  fragmentary 
way  in  our  actual  human  experience.  A  thing  in  itself 
outside  of  experience  can  solve  no  problems  and  can  be  of 
no  possible  interest  to  us.  It  is  not  merely  problematic, 
but  it  is  due  to  a  false  abstraction  —  the  supposition  that 
things  can  exist  by  themselves  without  making  differences 
to  other  individuals.  We  must  hold  that  it  is  precisely 
through  the  differences  that  individuals  make  in  definite 
contexts  that  they  can  be  known.  And  they  are  precisely 
such  as  we  must  take  them,  in  such  contexts. 

Once  we  frankly  and  thoroughly  apply  the  pragmatic 
method  to  the  taking  of  experience,  we  can  avoid  the  pit- 
falls into  which  Kant  fell  on  account  of  his  false  distinction 
between  reality  as  experienced  and  things  in  themselves. 
Take,  in  the  first  place,  the  ideal  synthesisjaf  .inner ^experi- 
ence, or  the  ego.  We  must  hold  here  that  "the  soul  is 
substance," 1  in  so  far  as  we  can  recognize  constancy  in 
the  series  of  its  processes,  and  predict  its  conduct.  This 
is  the  only  practical  significance  of  substance.  We  must 
hold,  secondly,  that  the  soul  is  "as  regards  its  quality 
simple  "  in  so  far  as  we  can  take  it  as  such,  that  is,  in  so  far 
as  one  idea  or  purpose  can  be  seen  to  run  through  it.  This 
does  not  prevent  its  owning  a  complexity  of  processes; 
1  Compare  op.  cit.,  p.  281,  "  Paralogisms  of  Pure  Reason." 


The  Categories  of  Intelligence  59 

and  both  in  ordinary  life  and  in  pathological  cases  we  know 
that  the  self  may  be  far  from  being  systematically  unified. 
In  ordinary  life,  the  self  may  hang  together  merely  by  con- 
tiguity of  interest;  and  in  pathological  cases,  even  this  ex- 
ternal thread  may  be  broken.  As  regards  the  numerical 
identity  of  the  soul  at  different  times,  this  again  can  only 
have  pragmatic  meaning,  that  is,  as  a  series  of  processes 
realizing  a  unique  will  throughout  the  shifting  fringes,  and 
thus  distinguishable  from  other  self  histories.  If  we  look 
for  an  identical  block  of  being,  certainly  there  is  nothing 
in  our  experience  to  warrant  assuming  any  such  numerical 
identity.  The  soul  is  numerically  distinct,  because  it  can 
be  distinguished  from  other  souls  with  their  streams  of 
processes.  Lastly  we  can  agree  with  Kant  that  the  soul 
"is  in  relation  to  possible  objects  of  space."  With  Kant 
we  would  adopt  empirical  realism.  In  his  own  words,  "  all 
external  perception  proves  immediately  something  real  in 
space  or  rather  is  that  real  itself,"1  though  without  Kant's 
implication  of  the  shadow  of  a  thing  in  itself  in  the  back- 
ground. 

In  our  finite  experience,  we  must  hold  that  the  unity  of 
the  self  is  a  goal  to  be  accomplished,  rather  than  a  finished 
fact.  We  must  substitute  for  the  block  unity  of  a  static 
conception  of  the  soul  the  dynamic  unity  of  a  conative 
direction  or  purpose  to  be  realized,  which  makes  the  parts 
hang  together  by  virtue  of  this  realization.  This  concep- 
tion of  unity  differs  from  that  of  pure  associationism, 
which  regards  the  self  as  a  mere  collection  of  static 
ideas  without  any  internal  cement  which  binds  those 
bits  together.  On  the  other  hand,  this  view  differs  from 
the  old  soul  theory,  which  evidently  Kant  had  in  mind,  of 
1  op.  fit.,  pp.  304  fi. 


6o  Truth  and  Reality 

a  simple,  identical,  static  entity  which  must  be  added  to  the 
successive  processes  of  consciousness.     Such  an  entity,  it  is 
easy  to  see,  is  pragmatically  useless.     The  only  unity  which 
can  be  of  pragmatic  value  must  be  the  dynamic  coherency 
and  direction  of  the  successive  states  within  an  idea  or  pur- 
pose.    Thus  we  dodge  the  formidable  so-called  "paralo- 
gisms "  of  pure  reason,  which  are  only  Kantian  scarecrows. 
If,  again,  we  take  up  the  ideal  synthesis  of  outer^expe- 
rience  or  nature,  we  find  the  pragmatic  method  equally 
clarifying.     Here,  too,  we  must  be  satisfied  to  take  reality 
piecemeal  and  for  what  it  is  in  experience.     And  thus  we 
shall  steer  clear  of  the  Kantian  antinomies.1     Nature  can 
be  taken  as  a  series  of  conditions  just  in  so  far  as  it  is  con- 
venient  so   to  take  it.     We  are  always   concerned  with 
special  problems  in  dealing  with  our  world.     Our  interest  in 
nature  has  to  do  with  the  prediction  and  control  of  certain 
practical  situations,  not  with  nature  in  the  abstract ;  and 
we  must  trace  these  conditions  just  in  so  far  as  the  needs  of 
prediction  require.    Absolute  completeness  of  conditions  is 
a  matter  of  theoretical  abstraction.     Space  and  time,  as 
quantitative  series,  are  merely  our  ideal  tools  for  dealing 
with  the  world  of  experience,  as  Kant  has  truly  shown. 
Following  them  out  to  infinity  will  be  at  best  a  tiresome 
play,  on  the  part  of  the  faculty  of  ideal  construction,  and 
could  have  nothing  to  do  with  reality.     Whether  reality  is 
infinite  in  time  and  space  cannot  be  settled  a  priori,  but 
must  be  determined  with  reference  to  the  needs  of  actual 
experience.     And   here   the   extent  of  reality,  in   either 
space  or  time,  is  only  of  interest  in  so  far  as  it  helps  us  to 
describe  and  orient  ourselves  within  the  world  with  which 
we  must  deal. 

1  Compare  op.  «'/.,  p.  344. 


The  Categories  of  Intelligence  61 

Since  we  cannot  conceive  change  to  have  originated 
from  the  unchanging,  we  can  theoretically  extend  our 
ideal  construction  of  time  indefinitely  back.  The  extent 
of  space  has  interest  for  us  only  in  determining  the  rela- 
tions of  energies  in  space.  And  these  relations  may  be 
finite,  whether  space  itself  is  infinite  or  not. 

When  we  come  to  the  question  of  the  divisibility  of  the 
objects  of  our  outer  experience,  here  again  we  must  pro- 
ceed pragmatically.  Our  mathematical  quantities  are  in- 
deed infinitely  divisible  by  definition.  Not  so  the  empirical 
world.  *  This  is  only  as  divisible  as  we  can  take  it  for  the 
purposes  of  conduct.  Whatever  may  be  decided  as  to  the 
existence  of  atoms  and  electrons,  there  certainly  is  no 
evidence  of  infinite  divisibility. 

If  we  take,  again,  the  question  of  origination,  or  causal- 
ity versus  freedom,  the  pragmatic  way  of  taking  reality 
recognizes,  on  the  one  hand,  that  there  are  certain  constan- 
cies or  identities  in  our  world  of  experience,  otherwise  we 
could  not  take  our  objects  twice ;  we  could  not  have  the 
same  meaning  over  again.  We  could  have  no  prediction, 
and  therefore  no  science.  On  the  other  hand,  there  seems 
to  be  a  certain  amount  of  novelty;  of  new  accretion  to 
reality,  at  least  in  certain  spots.  So  it  seems  to  our  finite 
experience,  at  any  rate.  What  we  must  modestly  do  in 
dealing  with  facts,  is,  to  render  unto  Caesar  that  which  is 
Caesar's,  and  take  reality  as  we  find  it. 

This  is  equally  true  as  regards  the  problem  of  necessity 
and  contingency.  There  can  be,  so  far  as  we  can  see,  no 
isolated,  indifferent  facts.  The  various  centers  or  energies 
must  hang  together  within  certain  contexts.  The  only  con- 
text which  is  theoretically  self-existing  and  self-explanatory 
is  the  total  dynamic  whole  of  reality.  This  does  not  mean, 


62  Truth  and  Reality 

however,  that  either  the  whole  or  the  parts  are  absolutely 
fixed  or  ready  made ;  that  reality  in  the  making  might  not 
have  been  otherwise.  We  are  dealing  here  with  ideals 
which  we  must  try  on  so  far  as  they  will  work.  Thus  the 
Kantian  antinomies  as  regards  our  attempted  synthesis  of 
nature  disappear  with  the  pragmatic  or  instrumental  view 
of  truth,  on  the  one  hand,  and  the  banishing  of  the  fictitious 
things  in  themselves  on  the  other. 

Taking  up,  in  the  third  place,  the  demand  for  an  ideal 
unitjLof  j)ur  social  experience  or  history,  here  too  we  must 
be  satisfied  with  this  same  pragmatic  method  of  procedure. 
Empirically  viewed,  there  seems  to  be  no  such  thing  as 
history.  There  are  rather  various  histories,  individual  and 
national,  which  sometimes  overlap  and  sometimes  fail  to 
do  so.  •  If  there  is  to  be  an  ideal  whole  of  history,  there- 
fore, we  cannot  look  for  it  in  the  past,  with  its  many  more 
or  less  separate  streams  of  civilization ;  but  we  must  look 
for  it  in  the  future.  Such  unity  of  common  sympathy  and 
common  understanding  seems  to  be  more,  at  any  rate,  than 
a  dream.  So  far  as  human  life  on  earth  is  concerned,  it 
is  being  swept  more  and  more  into  the  whirlpool  of  inter- 
national agitation,  commerce  and  education.  And  it  seems 
likely,  therefore,  that  in  the  try-out  of  various  ideals,  now 
competing  for  supremacy,  certain  common  standards  of 
conduct  will  result. 

The  unity  of  history,  like  the  unity  of  the  individual 
self,  means  the  convergence  towards  a  common  ideal.  It 
means  the  thread  of  an  identical  will  or  purpose,  running 
through  the  many  individual  and  national  histories  with 
their  motley  events.  Such  unity  may  provisionally  be 
communicated  to  the  larger  masses  of  individuals  and  na- 
tions, by  the  imitation  of  a  great  personality,  which  thus 


The  Categories  of  Intelligence  63 

comes  to  set  his  stamp  upon  events.  In  the  long  run, 
however,  ideals,  whether  personal  or  impersonal,  must  be 
measured  by  their  capacjty_tojan.ify  and  satisfy  the  com- 
plex demands  of  human  wills.  Thus  we  can  understand 
the  historic  life,  when  we  can  follow  the  transitions  of 
experience  through  the  identical  ideals  or  purposes  on 
which  the  events  converge. 

We  have  discussed  so  far  three  forms,  which  our  ideal 
feeling  for  wholeness  takes  in  its  realization  in  experience, 
namely,  the  realization  of  a  whole  of  our  inner  life,  or  the 
unitary' self ;  the  realization  of  a  whole  of  our  outer  world, 
or  the  systematic  unity  of  nature  ;  and  the  realization  of  a 
whole  in  our  fellow  world,  or  the  systematic  unity  of 
history.  We  must  still  take  another  step.  Our  mental 
constitution  is  such  that  we  could  not  rest  content  with 
these  forms  of  ideal  unity,  standing  side  by  side.  We  de- 
mand a  still  more  comprehensive  form ;  namely,  the  com- 
plete synthesis  of  all  experience,  or  the  absolute.  With 
Kant,  I  would  insist  that  such  a  unity  is  an  ideal  of  our 
reason,  a  regulative  principle  in  the  unification  of  our 
experience.  It  is  a  f|i£h  that,  somehow,  the  universe  as  a 
whole  hangs  together;  that  we  can  pass  directly,  or  by 
means  of  intermediaries,  from  one  part  of  our  world  to  an- 
other without  break.  As  such  an  ideal,  or  law  of  totality, 
the  concept  of  the  absolute  has  a  legitimate  function  in 
experience.  In  other  words,  the  ideal  of  knowledge  is 
that  of  a  fully  organized,  systematic  unity  of  all  facts  of 
experience. 

We  have  no_right,  however,  to_  hyppstatize  such  a  unity 
of  experience  into  an  objective  existence.  Kant  has  done 
immortal  service  in  showing  that  no  a  priori  proof  of  the 
existence  of  such  a  unity  of  experience,  including  and  con- 


64  Truth  and  Reality 

stituting  reality  as  a  whole,  is  possible.  The  traditional 
proofs  of  such  an  absolutely  necessary  experience  are 
inconclusive,  if  not  question  begging.  We  can  of  course 
have  the  idea  of  such  a  being.  There  is  nothing  inconsist- 
ent in  the  concept  of  the  absolute.  We  can  therefore 
think  of  it  as  having  existence,  but  no  thinking  of  ours 
can  constitute  such  an  existence.  This  must  be  proven, 
if  at  all,  ray-ott^success  in  using  the  hypothesis  in  meeting 
the  actual  needs  of  experience.  It  cannot  be  proven  a 
priori. 

Finally,  the  concept  of  Gq£,  and  the  proof  for  the  exist- 
ence of  God,  need  have  nothing  to  do  with  such  an  as- 
sumption in  regard  to  the  totality  of  being.  In  any  case, 
there  is  no  reason  why  we  should  worship  existence  as  a 
whole.  Our  faith  in  the  moral  law,  and  in  its  being  a  valid 
expression  of  our  universe,  may  lead  us,  as  it  led  Kant,  to 
the  recognition  of  a  personal  finite  consciousness  who  em- 
bodies in  an  effective  way  our  moral  demands.  But  this 
has  nothing  to  do  with  the  conception  of  the  totality  of 
being. 

Our  feeling  for  beauty,  our  striving  for  order  and  unity 
must  indicate  that  the  universe  cannot  at  any  rate  be 
foreign  or  hostile  to  such  demands,  for  we  are  part  of  the 
universe ;  and  our  ideal  demands  are  the  last  word  of  its 
long,  groping  and  struggling  evolutionary  history. 


PART  II 
THE  NATURE  OF  TRUTH 


CHAPTER   IV 

THE  TRUTH  PROCESS 

IN  discussing  the  thought  process,  I  wish  first  of  all  to 
differentiate  thought  from  other  types  of  meaning ;  in  the 
second  place,  I  want  to  show  the  relation  of  thought  to 
language ;  in  the  third  place,  I  want  to  make  some  com- 
ments on  the  psychological  investigations  of  thought ;  and 
in  the  fourth  place,  I  shall  try  to  define  the  thought  attitude 
itself. 


In  the  first  place,  in  discussing  the  thought  process,  we 
must  be  careful  to  differentiate  thought  from  the  simpler, 
prelogical  stages  in  the  development  of  meaning,  as  well 
as  from  other  types  of  organized  meaning.  Not  all  con- 
sciousness of  the  meaning  types  can  be  identified  with  judg- 
ment, if  by  judgment  we  mean  being  awake  or  actively 
controlling  the  stream  of  consciousness.  Already  on  the 
perceptual  level  we  have  cumulating  meaning.  The  series 
of  impressions  is  unified  by  the  impulsive  interest.  They 
overlap  as  warm,  living  sensations,  as  the  tones  of  the 
melody,  and  are  cemented  into  a  complex  affective  disposi- 
tion. If  that  is  true  on  the  perceptual  level,  it  is  still  more 
obvious  on  the  level  of  associative  memory.  Here  the 
idea  gets  its  significant  coloring  from  the  suggested  con- 
text of  contiguity  or  similarity.  Yet  so  long  as  the  control 
of  the  train  of  images  is  impulsive  merely,  we  cannot  call 

67 


68  Truth  and  Reality 

the  suggestiveness  of  context  a  case  of  judgment.  We 
must  recognize  contexts,  perceptual  and  ideational,  built  by 
prelogical  interest  and  ready  made  when  we  wake  up  to 
think. 

Not  only  does  unification  into  persistent  content-clusters, 
in  the  way  of  sensory  complication  and  association  of 
images,  take  place  on  the  impulsive  level  of  development. 
Discrimination,  too,  begins  on  the  prelogical  level.  It  may 
be  ^voluntary.  Take  Martineau's  familiar  illustration  of 
the  billiard  balls.  The  child's  attention  singles  out  the 
moving  billiard  ball  from  its  context.  When  a  ball  of  an- 
other color  is  exchanged  for  the  former,  attention  may 
detach  the  quality  of  color ;  and  so  with  the  form  and  other 
properties.  Having  had  experience  with  a  bitter-tasting 
fluid  in  a  bottle,  the  child  turns  its  head  away  from  the 
medicine.  In  the  confusion  of  odors,  the  faithful  dog 
singles  out  the  trail  of  the  master.  But  these  discrimina- 
tions are  quite  involuntary  and  cannot,  in  any  true  sense, 
be  termed  judgments.  When  the  judging  process  proper 
begins,  it  already  possesses,  as  a  result  of  involuntary  dis- 
crimination and  abstraction,  a  wealth  not  only  of  concrete 
objects,  but  also  of  abstract  qualities  and  relations.  This 
must  be  kept  in  mind  when  we  come  to  define  the  nature 
of  the  judging  process.  Not  all  abstractions  are  concepts ; 
and  acting  upon  an  abstraction  does  not  necessarily  imply 
a  judgment.  The  dog  identifies  the  tramp  type,  the  duck 
identifies  the  watery  kind  of  thing,  but  not  by  judgment. 

Another  caution,  which  must  be  remembered,  is  that  the 
child  receives  the  benefit  of  a  great  deal  of  thinking,  on 
the  part  of  society,  which  has  passed  into  convention  and 
custom.  We  are  born  into  a  world  of  certain  thought- 
fashions,  as  into  fashions  of  clothes  and  manners.  We 


The  Truth  Process  69 

imitate  the  conventional  attitudes  about  us  as  regards 
science,  and  politics,  and  other  important  adjustments 
to  contemporary  life.  We  also  imitate  the  customs,  which 
have  been  handed  down  to  us  from  time  immemorial, 
and  which,  unlike  our  laws  and  science,  do  not  appear  to 
be  man-made,  though  they  are  themselves  the  survivals 
of  forgotten  inventions.  Whether  our  imitation  is  due  to 
contemporary  prestige,  or  to  the  prestige  conferred  by 
time  and  ancestral  association,  in  either  case  we  must  not 
mistake  such  adjustments  for  thinking,  however  much 
thinking  may  have  been  involved  originally  in  formulating 
those  social  axioms  which  we  are  now  taking  for  granted. 
The  result  of  such  imitation  is  that  society  has  the  appear- 
ance of  doing  a  great  cfeal  more  thinking  than  it  does.  We 
speak  glibly  about  evolution,  and  gravitation,  and  other 
fundamental  doctrines,  without  knowing  as  a  rule  the 
reasons  upon  which  they  are  based.  We  take  them  because 
they  are  the  thing.  They  are  part  of  our  social  atmosphere. 
As  a  matter  of  fact,  we  do  but  little  thinking,  and  that 
usually  about  only  a  small  part  of  experience.  The  rest 
we  take  on  authority  and  prestige. 

Even  the  adaptation  of  means  to  ends  need  not  involve 
thought.  It  may  be  due  to  instinct  or  ordinary  association. 
We  ought  in  justice  to  apply  the  same  criterion  to  human 
conduct  as  we  do  to  that  of  animals  in  general.  If  we  do, 
however,  it  is  likely  to  play  havoc  with  our  cut-and-dried 
logical  schemes.  We  will  find  that  with  us,  as  with  the 
animals  below  us,  the  greater  part  of  the  conduct,  which 
has  the  appearance  of  being  intelligent,  is  due  to  habit  and 
the  imitation  of  tradition.  In  the  case  of  human  conduct, 
as  in  the  case  of  animals,  the  criterion  of  thinking  must  be 
the  ability  to  adapt  one's  self  to  a  novel  situation  on  the  basis 


/o  Truth  and  Reality 

of  identical  characters,  which  we  select  from  the  concrete 
complex  and  substitute  for  it.  Thinking  is  a  form  of  voli- 
tional conduct,  which  asks  the  why  and  whither ;  which 
implies  reasons  or  relations  to  a  context ;  and  which  termi- 
nates expressly  or  impliedly  in  a  definition;  This  is  such 
a  situation  as  can  be  met  on  the  basis  of  such  an  identical 
character  as  ascertained  through  previous  experience. 
Thinking  always  means  an  active  singling  out  of  a  relevant 
character  —  a  quality  or  relation.  It  is  the  conscious, 
active  control  of  a  situation  on  the  basis  of  a  selected  con- 
tent, whether  that  situation  be  associative  or  perceptual, 
inner  or  outer,  and  however  much  it  may  differ  in  other 
respects  from  the  original  situation. 

We  have  tried  to  differentiate  thought  from  the  more 
primitive  stages  of  cumulative  meaning,  such  as  learning 
by  habit  and  association.  Thought,  while  utilizing  the  per- 
ceptual and  associative  stages  of  meaning,  puts  a  new 
stamp  upon  them.  It  differs  from  these  by  involving 
organized  control  of  the  perceptual  and  associative  stream 
of  processes ;  by  the  deliberate  singling  out  of  a  relevant 
character  from  the  concrete  situation  and  the  conscious 
substituting  of  this  for  the  whole.  It  thus  enables  us  to 
meet  new  situations  on  the  basis  of  identical  characteristics, 
where  habit  and  memory  are  limited  to  concrete  repetition. 
The  Indian  of  the  story,  once  having  had  the  taste  of  roast 
pig  from  the  burning  of  his  wigwam,  proceeds  to  burn  the 
wigwam  every  time  he  wants  roast  pig,  while  reason  would 
enable  him  to  abstract  the  essential  relation  and  proceed  on 
the  basis  of  it.  -w^  ^  ^  tfO-  ecov^w^  rt  tv^fiww  . 

While  thought  thus  enables  us  to  economize  greatly  the 
life  of  habit  and  memory,  it  must  not  be  forgotten  that  in 
turn  thought  presupposes  these  more  concrete  forms  of 


The   Truth  Process  71 

unity  in  order  to  do  its  work.  Complication  and  associa- 
tion furnish  thought,  on  the  one  hand,  the  storehouse  from 
which  it  can  draw  in  its  search  for  relevant  characteristics. 
The  peculiar  set  of  thought  can  only  suggest  the  appro- 
priate characteristics,  when  these  are  already  strung  by 
contiguities  and  similarities  within  the  network  of  experi- 
ence. The  thought  interest  selects  rather  than  -makes  the 
significant  relations.  It  runs  through  and  intersects  the 
previous  concrete  unities  in  all  sorts  of  ways,  guided  by  its 
dominant  tendency.  On  the  other  hand,  thought  could 
not  arrive  at  its  end,  identify  its  proper  objects,  unless 
the  concrete  unities  were  suggested  on  the  basis  of  thought's 
abstractions.  It  is  the  merit  of  these  abstractions  that  they 
lead  us  to  the  concrete  situations  which  we  must  meet 
And  this  concrete  context  must  be  supplied  by  perceptual 
complication  and  memory.  To  fail  to  see  this  relation  of 
thought  to  the  more  primitive  unities  is  to  fail  to  understand 
thought's  proper  function  in  experience,  which  is  to  termi- 
nate in  the  concrete  situation.  The  value  of  our  theory  of 
eclipses  is  to  enable  us  to  meet  concrete  eclipses.  The 
value  of  the  search  for  the  forgotten  name  is  to  identify  a 
concrete  individual. 

While  we  must  differentiate  thought  from  the  simpler 
unities  of  experience,  we  must  also  distinguish  it  from  other 
forms  of  ideal  synthesis,  which,  like  thought,  involve  ideal 
construction  and  organization  by  purpose,  such  as  esthetic 
wholes.  It  has  sometimes  been  argued  that  the  esthetic 
unity,  with  its  fluent  and  harmonious  synthesis  of  parts,  is 
the  goal  of  the  thought  process.  Whether  esthetic  unity  is 
a  higher  form  of  unity  than  thought  unity  is  not  a  point  for 
discussion  here.  In  any  case,  we  must  hold  that  it  is  differ- 
ent. We  have  seen  that  thought  involves  the  conscious- 


72  Truth  and  Reality 

ness  of  active  analysis  or  control  of  the  situation.  The 
previous  adjustment  is  somehow  upset,  and  we  must 
meet  the  situation  in  a  new  way.  This  means  unrest 
until  the  problem  is  solved,  until  the  curiosity  is  satis- 
fied. While  there  is  suggestion  of  unity  in  obedience 
to  a  purpose,  this  is  only  gotten  by  hesitation  and  the 
pondering  of  alternatives.  The  esthetic  consciousness  is 
fundamentally  different.  Esthetic  unity  is  spontaneously 
suggested  to  the  spectator.  It  holds  us  instead  of  our 
holding  it.  In  the  immediate  suggestion  of  ideal  fluency 
and  fitness,  it  is  at  the  other  extreme  from  thought.  If  the 
esthetic  object  puzzles  the  spectator,  if  it  requires  analysis 
in  order  to  be  understood,  if  it  suggests  improvement  or 
readjustment,  it  has  largely  nullified  its  claim  to  esthetic 
value.  It  must  be  capable  of  immediate  appreciation, 
without  previous  understanding.  In  its  harmonious  play 
of  parts,  in  the  ease  of  transition  from  content  to  content, 
in  the  involuntary,  clear  and  distinct  suggestion  of  the 
idea  or  universal,  lie  its  spontaneous  enjoyment  and  its 
title  to  being  art.  Mere  technic,  mere  elaborate  and 
puzzling  detail,  must  be  evaluated  from  some  other  point 
of  view  than  that  of  art. 

II 

Perhaps  the  greatest  source  of  confusion  in  regard  to  the 
thought  process  is  due  to  language.  It  is  true  that  lan- 
guage is  by  far  the  most  important  tool  in  the  service  of 
thought,  and  that  thought  could  progress  but  to  a  rudi- 
mentary extent,  if  it  were  not  for  language.  Language  is 
to  thought  a  sort  of  sixth  sense.  By  its  artificial  symbols 
and  its  network  of  relations,  by  "  winged  words,"  it  enables 
thought  to  intuit  immediately  its  own  past  mind  and  the 


The  Truth  Process  73 

expressed  mind  of  others.  But  it  is  not  true,  either  from 
the  point  of  view  of  race  history  or  of  individual  history, 
that  language  and  thought  necessarily  go  together.  In  the 
first  place,  we  are  now  agreed  that  there  can  be  thought 
without  language.  Other  forms  of  symbolism,  perceptual 
or  ideal,  may  serve  the  instrumental  needs  of  thought. 
We  do  not  always  formulate  our  thinking  into  words.  If 
we  look  at  the  development  of  language  again,  either  from 
the  point  of  view  of  the  evolution  of  the  race  or  of  the  indi- 
vidual, we  must  recognize  that  language  runs  parallel  to  the 
whole  story  of  mental  development  and  is  by  no  means 
limited  to  the  level  of  thought  development.  Phyloge- 
netically,  language  begins  on  the  perceptual  level,  both  as 
regards  emotional  and  descriptive  signs.  Animals,  which 
certainly  show  no  signs  of  thought  and  may  not  even  in- 
dicate the  presence  of  images,  still  make  themselves  known 
to  each  other,  and  elicit  certain  types  of  conduct  by  means 
of  certain  sounds  and  gestures.  On  the  level  of  associative 
memory,  greater  complexity  of  such  signs  would  naturally 
manifest  itself.  But  it  is  with  analysis  and  abstraction,  or 
on  the  level  of  thought  and  its  inventiveness,  that  artificial 
language  is  first  formed  with  its  immense  variety  of  sym- 
bolism. Where  such  inventiveness  enters  in,  you  do,  of 
course,  satisfy  the  criterion  of  thought.  The  greater 
number  of  human  beings,  however,  get  the  inventions  of 
language,  as  they  get  other  inventions,  viz.,  second  hand. 
When  thus  imitated,  language,  no  more  than  the  use  of 
any  other  ready-made  invention,  implies  thinking. 

If  we  look  at  the  matter,  again,  from  the  point  of  view 
of  individual  history  or  ontogenetically,  we  know  that  a 
child  imitates  language,  as  it  imitates  the  other  gestures 
and  conduct  about  it,  without  question  or  deliberation.  It 


74  Truth  and  Reality 

simply  cannot  help  trying  to  perform  the  movements  and 
expressions  of  those  immediately  about  it.  It  is  only  later 
in  life,  if  at  all,  that  the  net  results  of  human  development, 
as  crystallized  in  words,  come  to  signify  thinking  to  the 
individual.  Language,  in  other  words,  starts  as  one  per- 
ceptual form  of  reaction.  It  develops  into  one  kind  of 
memory  picture  and  establishes  connection  with  other 
pictures  and  actions  by  the  laws  of  association,  though  its 
greater  economy  tends  to  make  it  supplant  the  more  con- 
crete forms  of  associative  pictures.  Language  may  stand 
for  all  sorts  of  mental  states.  It  may  be  the  name  of  a 
perceptual  complication,  such  as  a  tree  or  a  stone.  It  may 
stand  for  a  concrete  image.  It  may  symbolize  an  abstract 
relation  or  quality.  But  one  thing  is  sure,  we  cannot  take 
language  as  the  synonym  of  thought.  Even  propositions, 
though  they  symbolize  judgment  on  the  part  of  some  one, 
certainly  are  not  judgments  as  they  are  found  in  the  logic 
books,  or  in  our  school  primers.  Such  propositions  as  :  Is 
the  dog  white  ?  Yes,  the  dog  is  white,  and  other  equally 
solemn  ones,  probably  did  not  convey  judgments  to  the 
youthful  seeker  after  wisdom  of  the  primary  grade ;  nor 
do  the  conventional  propositions  of  the  logic  books,  such 
as  :  All  men  are  mortal ;  Socrates  is  a  man ;  therefore,  Soc- 
rates is  mortal,  convey  much  of  the  significance  of  the 
thought  process  to  the  average  college  sophomore.  This 
significance  can  only  be  seen  when  we  abandon  our  abstract 
formalism  and  return  to  the  function  of  language  in  the 
active,  living  thought  situation,  with  its  problems,  its  reso- 
lution into  a  definite  plan  of  procedure  and  its  systematic 
reasons.  Then  we  see  that  it  is  first  through  observing  the 
characteristics  of  such  men  as  Socrates  that  we  see  what 
holds  for  their  kind ;  and  afterwards  all  we  have  to  do  is 


The  Truth  Process  75 

to  identify  the  individual's  kind  in  order  to  determine 
expectancy  as  regards  mortality  or  other  characters. 

Language,  moreover,  like  all  tools,  has  its  limitations. 
It  must  resort  to  all  sorts  of  makeshifts  to  symbolize  the  com- 
plexity of  thought.  It  must  stereotype  into  static  pictures 
thought's  transitive  relations.  It  gives  the  appearance  of 
juxtapositions  of  subjects  and  copulas  and  predicates.  It 
makes  relations  and  qualities  appear  as  entities  or  sub- 
stances. It  gives  to  individuals  an  isolation  and  fixity 
which  a.re  foreign  to  the  real  world  of  fluent  transitions. 
No  wonder  this  makes  thought  appear  a  hopeless  mass  of 
chopped-up  abstractions  to  one  who  has  not  grasped  the 
instrumental  significance  of  language.  To  one  who  has 
grasped  this,  language  becomes  a  marvelous  framework  or 
system  of  pegs  for  recording,  communicating  and  fixating 
the  relative  constancies  of  our  fluent  inner  meanings. 

Nominalism,  by  confusing  thought  with  language  —  re- 
ducing concepts  to  mere  terms,  judgments  to  the  separation 
or  juxtaposition  of  terms,  and  reasoning  to  the  juxtaposition 
of  propositions  —  makes  thought  seem  artificial  and  arbi- 
trary. With  Bergson  it  makes  thought  a  series  of  static  pic- 
tures, like  the  photographs  of  the  cinematograph,  but  in  no 
respect  imitating  reality.  Nominalism  first  makes  a  carica- 
ture of  thought  and  then  pronounces  it  impossible,  as  it 
certainly  is  on  nominalist  principles.  What  nominalism 
forgets  is  that  the  symbols  need  in  no  wise  resemble  the 
realities  they  stand  for.  The  bill  of  fare  isn't  at  all  like  the 
things  it  stands  for,  and  yet  it  may  be  a  very  accurate  and 
useful  bill  of  fare.  Were  thought  as  arbitrary  as  nomi- 
nalism makes  it,  we  cannot  see  of  what  use  it  could  possibly 
be  in  meeting  reality. 

We  must  also  bear  in  mind  that  conveying  thought  is 


76  Truth  and  Reality 

only  part,  and  a  comparatively  small  part,  of  the  function 
of  language.  Words  serve  the  purpose  of  calling  up  trains 
of  concrete  images  and  awakening  emotional  attitudes 
more  often  than  of  conveying  thought.  The  figure,  to  cru- 
cify on  a  cross  of  gold,  served  some  years  ago  to  stampede 
a  whole  political  convention,  yet  what  the  words  conveyed 
was  not  thought,  but  imagery  suffused  with  religious  emo- 
tion. The  cry  of  the  full  dinner  pail  once  won  a  presi- 
dential election,  but  its  appeal  was  to  the  stomach  not  to 
reason.  Some  words  are  simply  charged  with  emotional  en- 
thusiasm and  impulsive  energy,  such  as  the  words,  Liberty, 
Fraternity  and  Equality,  in  the  days  of  the  French  Revolu- 
tion. Even  in  the  acceptance  of  certain  philosophical 
theories  such  as  the  Absolute,  or  the  Unknowable,  or 
idealism  or  realism,  or  Christian  Science,  the  convincing- 
ness may  not  be  due  to  thought,  which  is  generally  hard 
to  find  and  which  itself  is  apt  to  consist  in  reasons  trumped 
up  after  the  fact.  The  conviction  is  apt  to  rest  upon  the 
play  of  imagination,  with  the  suggested  emotions,  which 
the  words  call  forth.  Hence,  too,  the  theological  convinc- 
ingness of  such  terms  as  Unitarian  or  trinitarian  to  masses 
of  people  who  have  no  inkling  of  their  philosophical  signi- 
ficance. The  vitality  of  language  lies  precisely  in  its  be- 
ing woven  into  the  whole  tissue  of  life  —  imaginative  and 
emotional,  as  well  as  intellectual. 

Ill 

If  we  take  up  again  the  psychological  analysis  of  thought, 
this  has  been  scarcely  more  satisfactory  than  the  lexico- 
graphical account  of  the  old  formal  logic.  There  has  been, 
in  the  first  place,  a  very  vague  consciousness  as  to  what 
thought  is.  In  a  large  number  of  the  experimental  in- 


The  Truth  Process  77 

stances  reported,  such  as,  London  is  to  England  as  Paris 
is  to  — ,  it  is  not  necessary  to  assume  anything  but  passive 
association  in  furnishing  the  answer.  It  is  extremely 
difficult  to  determine,  under  the  artificial  conditions  of  the 
laboratory,  whether  one  is  dealing  with  a  genuine  case  of 
thought  consciousness  or  not.  There  is  no  a  priori  way 
of  telling  whether  a  certain  group  of  symbols  or  a  certain 
situation  means  a  real  thought  process  to  the  individual 
subject  or  not.  It  might  again  be  a  case  of  thought  con- 
sciousness, on  the  part  of  the  operator  who  devises  the 
situation,  but  merely  a  matter  of  habitual  association  on 
the  part  of  the  subject  There  is  no  way  of  determining 
in  the  abstract  when  you  have  a  genuine  case  of  thought, 
a  real  judgment.  This  can  only  be  done  with  reference  to 
the  situation  which  the  will  strives  to  meet.  A  statement 
which  symbolizes  thought  with  one,  may  symbolize  merely 
conventional  imitation  with  another. 

An  introspective  account  at  best  brings  out  primarily  the 
training  and  methods  of  thought  of  the  introspecting  indi- 
vidual. Hegel  gives  us  the  typical  introspective  Account 
in  his  Logic.  Here  the  category  of  being  suggests  with 
subjective  necessity  the  category  of  non-being;  and  this  in 
turn  the  category  of  becoming,  each  category  leading  into 
the  other  until  the  circle  is  complete.  But  the  implications 
and  stages  which  he  feels  to  be  so  binding  in  this  subjec- 
tive dialectic  are  chiefly  interesting  as  throwing  light  on 
Hegel's  own  mind.  His  transitions  have  not  proved  co- 
ercive even  over  those  who,  in  the  main,  adopt  Hegel's 
results.  They  certainly  throw  no  light  on  the  prelogical 
stages  of  mind.  All  the  way  from  Being  to  the  Absolute 
Idea,  we  move  within  the  universe  of  abstract  thought. 
That  one  steeped  in  a  scheme  of  logic  should  find  such 


78  Truth  and  Reality 

a  scheme  implied  in  his  own  thinking,  whether  in  formal 
or  experimental  introspection,  throws  considerable  light 
upon  the  nature  of  the  process  of  imitation,  but  not  upon 
the  process  of  judgment. 

While  again  it  is  true  that  thinking  terminates  in  types 
of  conduct  —  the  ability  to  meet  a  diversity  of  situations  in 
a  similar  way  —  it  is  not  true  that  wherever  we  find  types 
of  conduct,  there,  also,  we  have  judgment.  Here  again  we 
must  be  careful  not  to  stop  with  a  vague  genus,  but  also 
to  furnish  the  specific  differentia.  We  must  define  the 
kind  of  type  or  reflective  conduct  as  distinct  from  other 
types.  Instincts  and  impulses  also  prescribe  types  — 
vague,  general  types.  There  are  three  such  broad  types 
of  conduct  even  in  the  lowest  animals  —  things  to  appro- 
priate, things  to  get  away  from,  stimuli  to  reproduction. 
In  the  higher  grades  of  animal  life,  these  instinctive  types 
of  conduct  —  spontaneous  reactions  to  certain  kinds  of 
stimuli  —  become  much  more  numerous.  It  is  by  the  ex- 
amination of  conduct  —  the  conduct  of  animals,  of  the  de- 
veloping child,  of  the  grown  man  —  not  by  mere  introspec- 
tion, that  we  can  learn  to  differentiate  definitely  the  per- 
ceptual stage  of  conduct,  with  its  trial  and  error  method 
of  elimination  and  habit,  from  the  memory  stage  with  its 
short  cuts  for  the  concrete  reproduction  of  situations ;  and 
distinguish  definitely  both  of  these  from  the  stage  of  active 
analysis  and  synthesis  —  that  of  judgment.  Each  stage 
implies  its  own  type  of  conduct;  has  its  own  character- 
istics. The  suggestion  of  typical  response  differs  with 
each  stage.  The  sight  of  the  mouse  suggests  the  typical 
movement  of  the  cat,  the  meeting  of  a  friend  prompts  the 
proper  reaction  on  the  part  of  the  man,  the  request  of  the 
stranger  suggests  examining  his  credentials.  But  it  is  only 


The  Truth  Process  79 

on  the  last  stage  that  we  have  consciously  defined  types  or 
concepts. 

Language  fixes  the  more  important  thought  attitudes,  but 
it  is  too  abstract  and  stereotyped  to  fix  all.  Out  of  those 
again  that  language  has  fixed,  logic  selects  certain  ones 
which  are  most  convenient  in  studying  the  form  of  thought, 
viz. ,  the  categorical  types.  The  syllogism  is  such  a  linguis- 
tic device,  not  for  showing  how  people  do  think,  though 
sometimes  as  a  result  of  imitation  thought  may  flow  that 
way,  but  for  exhibiting  those  identities  which  make  think- 
ing valid. 

In  the  second  place,  the  psychologist's  analysis  has  been 
largely  irrelevant  to  the  real  problem  of  thought.  That  is 
true  especially  of  the  controversy  as  to  whether  there  is  im- 
ageless  thought,  which  has  been  so  prominent  of  late. 
There  doubtless  are  present  some  substantive  contents  — 
images,  verbal  or  concrete,  or  at  least  certain  kinesthetic 
sensations  in  the  head  and  perhaps  elsewhere.  There  can 
be  no  doubt  in  my  case  as  to  the  kinesthetic  sensations. 
I  would  not  call  them  images  in  my  case,  as  they  are  defi- 
nitely located  as  tensions  in  the  eyes,  the  facial  muscles, 
about  the  nose  and  forehead,  and  in  the  throat.  To  find  a 
case  in  the  midst  of  the  complexity  of  our  mental  life,  with 
its  mass  of  intra-  and  extra-organic  sensations,  of  a  pure  ab- 
stract consciousness  of  thought  transition,  with  all  other  con- 
tents psychologically  eliminated,  probably  is  more  than  the 
boasted  laboratory  method  is  likely  to  accomplish. 

One  reason  for  the  controversy  as  regards  imageless 
thought  is  probably  the  failure  to  distinguish  between  two 
kinds  of  thought  attitude — one  where  the  end  or  focal  idea 
is  more  or  less  vaguely  present,  but  where  the  context  or 
means  is  to  be  made  explicit  in  terms  of  this  end ;  the  other, 


8o  Truth  and  Reality 

where  we  start  with  the  consciousness  of  a  more  or  less  vague 
context,  or  means,  but  are  trying  lo  define  a  substantive 
content,  the  end.  The  former  case  can  be  illustrated  by 
any  attempt  to  meet  a  perceptual  or  ideal  situation,  where 
the  manipulating  of  a  given  situation  is  the  point  in  ques- 
tion. A  door  will  not  open,  and  so  we  must  cast  about  for 
means ;  we  must  analyze  the  situation,  to  discover  the  real 
relation  involved,  in  order  to  proceed  with  our  conduct.  But 
all  the  while,  there  is  present  in  the  perceptual  focus  of 
attention  the  substantive  content,  the  perceptual  door. 
The  second  case  might  be  illustrated  by  the  forgotten  name. 
The  actual  object,  the  name,  is  the  very  thing  that  won't 
come ;  and  so  the  will  in  seeking  it  must  set  to  work 
through  the  various  associative  tendencies  of  its  fringe  to 
bring  it  into  definite  consciousness.  Now  in  each  of  these 
two  cases,  substantive  imagery  plays  a  very  different  part. 
In  the  former  case,  a  substantive  picture  occupies  the  fore- 
ground of  consciousness  all  the  while.  In  the  latter  case, 
the  flights,  the  transitions  or  tensions,  are  the  prominent 
part  of  our  consciousness.  In  the  former  case,  the  pic- 
ture or  image  seems  to  constitute  the  end,  or  at  any  rate  to 
be  a  part  of  it.  In  the  latter  case,  the  imagery,  in  so  far  as 
it  is  present,  seems  largely  instrumental,  if  not  concomitant 
merely,  to  the  train  of  thought.  Those  who  maintain  im- 
ageless  thought  seem  to  have  in  mind  cases  where  transition 
stuff,  sensory  and  affective,  forms  thought's  only  instru- 
mental basis. 

Take  again  the  case  of  language.  We  may  attend  to 
the  words  as  conveying  the  thought  and  be  conscious  of 
the  niceties  of  the  style  thus  involved ;  or  we  may  be  ab- 
sorbed in  the  conative  tendency  itself,  the  transitive  flight 
of  thought ;  and  typography  and  style  then  drop  into  the 


The   Truth  Process  8 1 

fringe.  In  the  latter  case,  again,  the  stopping  of  the  atti- 
tude, in  order  to  introspect  it,  may  throw  into  prominence 
scenery  which  was  merely  concomitant  before,  conscious- 
ness being  changed  from  interest  in  the  objective  attitude 
to  interest  in  the  accessories.  No  doubt  the  form  of  the 
page  and  the  size  of  the  print  and  the  surroundings  made  a 
difference,  but  these  again  may  have  been  merely  concomi- 
tant to  the  conative  activity.  In  any  case,  the  perceptual  or 
ideational  pictures  do  not  constitute  the  thought  attitude,  as 
the  representative  theory  of  thought  would  have  us  believe. 
They  are  instruments  in  its  service,  the  perching  places  of 
its  flight.  But  the  flight  is  the  thing. 

IV 

The  thought  attitude  proper  means,  first  of  all,  the  active 
leading  or  control  of  the  flow  of  processes  by  a  conscious, 
organized  conative  purpose.  It  is  in  this  selective  leading, 
rather  than  in  the  type  of  imagery  found,  whether  rele- 
vant or  irrelevant  to  the  process,  that  the  essence  of  thought 
is  to  be  found.  To  this  concrete  or  verbal  imagery,  kin- 
esthetic  sensations,  etc.,  are  incidental.  The  controversy  as 
regards  imageless  thought,  if  it  has  served  no  other  purpose, 
has  at  least  brought  out  the  difference  as  regards  the  promi- 
nence and  types  of  imagery  in  connection  with  the  thought 
process.  It  is  evident  that  the  imagery  and  the  concomitant 
sensations  may  differ  widely  in  different  individuals.  But 
the  thought  process  itself  can  be  taken  as  the  same,  in  so  far 
as  it  points  to  and  terminates  in  the  same  aspect  of  the  situa- 
tion selected ;  in  so  far  as  it  leads  to  the  same  conduct. 
What  must  be  emphasized  is  that  it  is  the  conative  leading 
which  constitutes  the  core  of  thought,  not  the  imagery. 

This  leading,  this  sustained  attention,  this  control  of  the 

G 


82  Truth  and  Reality 

stream  of  processes  by  an  idea,  may  or  may  not  involve 
the  consciousness  of  the  feeling  of  effort.  Whether  this 
feeling  is  present  or  not  in  a  noticeable  way  depends  upon 
the  degree  in  which  we  are  baffled,  upon  the  fascination  of 
the  situation  in  question.  We  may  ourselves  set  the  puzzle. 
Our  whole  attention  may  be  absorbed  in  the  search  for 
means,  and  while  there  is  hesitation  and  analysis,  our  con- 
sciousness may  be  entirely  on  the  content  and  not  on  our 
subjective  attitude,  with  its  motor  symptoms.  What,  in  any 
case,  constitutes  the  activity  is  not  the  feeling  of  effort,  which 
is  a  mere  reflex  of  its  going  on,  but  the  sustained  attention, 
with  its  weighing  of  alternatives,  its  passing  in  survey  of 
the  various  tendencies  or  aspects  of  the  situation,  its  try- 
out  of  various  suggestions  in  order  to  hit  upon  the  relevant 
characteristics  or  relations  so  that  this  specific  type  of  con- 
duct may  go  on. 

Thought,  we  see,  therefore,  is  a  volitional  process.  It 
has  its  roots,  like  the  other  activities  of  our  conscious  life, 
in  our  impulsive  and  emotional  nature.  It  is  positive  and 
not  merely  negative  —  not  the  mere  absence  of  doubt,  but 
the  realization  of  a  specific  will.  It  may  start  in  the  prac- 
tical necessities  of  life  —  the  break-down  of  the  conventional 
and  habitual  as  regards  practical  adjustment.  It  may  start 
in  baffled  curiosity,  stimulated  by  the  unusual.  In  any 
case,  it  means  a  fresh  resolution  of  the  situation  involved, 
whether  perceptual  or  ideal.  It  means  getting  at  the 
character  of  reality  so  far  as  this  special  purpose  is  con- 
cerned. 

We  cannot  divorce  thought  from  the  deeper  will.  We 
cannot  draw  a  sharp  line  between  reason  and  instinct. 
Thought  is  not  the  mere  encrustation  on  the  stream  of  life, 
irrelevant  to  its  inner  nature.  It  is  not  the  subconscious, 


The  Truth  Process  83 

wedged  into  the  artificial  vice  of  the  brain.  Thought  is 
rooted  in  instinct  and  finds  its  fulfillment  in  realizing  the 
demands  of  instinct,  the  meaning  of  which  it  reveals. 
Thought  is  a  living,  moving  will,  a  will  which  has  set  itself 
a  definite  conscious  goal  —  the  regulation  of  its  intent  with 
reference  to  the  nature  of  the  environment.  It  is  will,  awake 
as  to  its  direction.  Instinct  bequeaths  to  thought  certain 
tendencies  or  demands,  among  them  the  theoretical  demands 
which  we  shall  examine  later.  Thought  bequeaths  to  in- 
stinct the  definiteness  of  articulate  and  self-conscious 
purpose,  instead  of  vague  groping  impulse.  All  the  while, 
however,  this  vaguer  life  is  in  the  fringe  of  thought.  It 
furnishes  in  large  part  the  motive  of  thought,  while  in  turn 
lighted  up  and  guided  as  to  its  direction.  Thought  is  not 
the  mere  focus,  but  the  total  set  or  determination,  which 
selects  and  guides.  The  value  of  the  subconscious  lies  in 
its  contributing  to  this  determination.  Its  reward  lies  in 
its  own  illumination. 

If  we  were  to  contrast  reason  and  instinct,  we  should 
say  that  it  is  instinct  which  is  stereotyped  and  predictable. 
Creativeness  lies  not  in  the  direction  of  animal  vagueness, 
but  in  the  direction  of  reason.  It  is  thought  which  sets 
us  free  from  the  slavery  to  the  past.  And  while  thought 
sometimes  proceeds  intuitively,  omitting  formal  steps  and 
intermediaries,  even  here  the  fruits  of  thought  usually  imply 
the  longer  and  more  laborious  processes  gone  through  pre- 
viously ;  and  in  any  case  the  intuitive  insight  would  not  come 
except  for  the  set  of  thought.  Furthermore,  if  it  comes  like 
a  gift,  it  must,  like  the  Greeks,  be  tested  before  it  can  be 
fully  trusted.  The  wisdom  of  the  subconscious  is  the  gift 
of  previous  thoughtfulness.  Its  authoritativeness  must  lie 
in  its  ability  to  meet  the  demands  of  experience. 


84  Truth  and  Reality 

Accompanying  this  state  of  deliberation,  this  weighing 
of  hypothesis,  this  casting  about  for  means,  there  is  the 
consciousness  of  motor  suspense  or  tension.  The  various 
tendencies  to  action  block  each  other  for  the  time  being. 
There  is  the  consciousness  of  uncertainty  or  doubt,  the 
attitude  of  waiting.  The  idea  of  proceeding  in  one  direc- 
tion, with  its  impulsive  tendency,  is  blocked  by  the  idea, 
immediately  brought  forward,  of  proceeding  in  another 
direction.  This  state  of  oscillation  or  permeability  may 
itself,  as  in  the  Hamlet  type,  form  a  cast  of  thought,  pre- 
venting action,  unless  broken  through  by  cumulative  impulse 
or  a  higher  resolution  of  thought. 

Thought,  further,  involves  a  feeling  of  fitness  when  the 
idea  terminates  in  its  intended  facts,  when  our  intent  is 
verified  and  our  conduct  again  proceeds.  This  means,  of 
course,  a  feeling  of  unfitness,  when  our  intent  fails  to  tally 
with  the  facts  and  when,  therefore,  either  the  idea  or  the 
reality  intended  must  be  altered  in  order  to  bring  about  the 
agreement.  Excepting  in  cases  where  our  will  makes  the 
idea  come  true,  as  in  some  cases  of  muscular  and  other 
bodily  adjustments  amenable  to  the  will,  our  idea  must 
respect  the  facts  and  terminate  in  them.  When  we  have 
such  a  feeling  of  fulfillment,  of  fluency  or  ease  in  the  res- 
olution of  the  thought  situation,  we  have  the  sentiment  of 
rationality.  And  this  can  only  be  disturbed,  in  the  par- 
ticular case,  when  there  is  a  fresh  discord  between  idea 
and  facts  and  a  call  for  a  fresh  resolution  of  the  situation, 
for  an  assimilation  of  new  data. 

Finally,  the  thought  process  is  a  unique  form  of  activity. 
It  cannot  be  resolved  into  more  of  perceptual  assimilation 
or  of  passive  association,  any  more  than  sustained  or  active 
attention  can  be  resolved  into  the  jerky,  impulsive  type. 


The  Truth  Process  85 

Thought  must,  of  course,  work  through  the  machinery  of 
association.  It  is  itself  one  type  of  the  associative  working 
of  mind,  both  as  regards  recall  and  as  regards  assimilation 
of  new  data.  What  is  unique  about  thought  is  its  intent, 
its  set,  its  activity.  And  this  intent  is  to  discover  the  lead- 
ing or  agreement  in  the  variety  of  facts  and  tendencies ;  to 
produce  point  for  point  correspondence  between  the  intent 
and  its  specific  facts  —  not  with  the  object  in  general  but 
the  object  in  so  far  as  it  is  intended.  The  formula  of  gravi- 
tation does  not  correspond  point  for  point  with  the  bodies 
in  space'  —  their  growth  and  life  history.  It  only  corre- 
sponds with  them  in  so  far  as  they  are  falling  matter. 

We  see  now  how  artificial  is  the  tripartite  division  of 
mind  into  ideation,  feeling  and  will.  The  truth  process 
involves  all  of  these.  It  is  the  realization  of  an  idea, 
selected  and  fixated  by  the  will,  which  has  a  definite 
hedonic  value,  as  the  process  fails  or  succeeds  of  realiza- 
tion. The  truth  process  is  self-realization — the  whole  self 
striving  to  realize  a  definite  end  —  the  will  to  know. 


CHAPTER  V 
.THE  MORPHOLOGY  OF  TRUTH 

IN  this  chapter  I  wish  to  sketch  briefly  the  various  stages 
of  the  truth  process.  We  realize  now  that  thought  is  a  liv- 
ing, unitary,  self-defining  activity.  It  knows  of  no  such  cut- 
and-dried  divisions  as  words  and  propositions.  These  are 
its  instruments,  not  its  constituents.  It  flows  over  the  nar- 
row and  arbitrary  limits  of  our  schemes  of  formal  logic.  It  is 
ever  alive  and  active,  selective  of  the  relevant  features  of 
the  situation,  prospective  with  questioning,  retrospective 
with  searching  for  means.  It  is  a  matrix  of  relations, 
reaching  forward  and  backward  and  throbbing  with  will  — 
not  the  pale  ghost  of  the  formal  proposition  or  syllogism, 
which,  however  important  for  the  effectiveness  of  thought's 
procedure,  are  only  its  artificial  tools. 

The  real  core  of  this  thought  activity  is  the  act  of  judg- 
ment And  judgment,  we  have  seen,  means  the  active  as- 
similation of  a  datum  in  terms  of  a  context ;  and,  in  turn, 
the  making  definite  of  the  context  in  terms  of  the  datum. 
Since  Spencer  we  have  come  to  regard  thought,  not  as  an 
idle  picture  show,  or  marshaling  of  formal  propositions,  as 
in  text-books  on  logic,  but  as  a  functional  adjustment  to  a 
larger  whole.  The  environment  of  thought  need  not  neces- 
sarily be  that  of  biological  survival,  though  that  was  the  ab- 
sorbing interest  in  the  early  development  of  thought. 
Thought  may  be  an  adjustment  to  an  ideal  context,  as  in 
the  working  out  of  a  geometrical  problem.  But  thought 
always  involves  a  problem  and  its  solution.  It  always  exists 

86 


The  Morphology  of  Truth  87 

for  a  purpose  which  is  to  be  defined  and  made  effective. 
There  is  no  thinking  in  the  abstract,  however  much  thought 
may  utilize  abstractions.  What  the  specific  context  which  is 
to  be  defined  is,  depends  upon  our  whole  volitional  attitude 
for  the  time  being,  for  all  real  thinking  is  live  thinking, 
throbs  with  desire  and  emotion.  The  context  may  be  the 
whole  of  things,  as  in  metaphysics.  It  may  be  chemical,  it 
may  be  domestic,  according  to  the  dominant  interest  at  the 
time.  We  must,  in  any  case,  understand  judgment  in  rela- 
tion to  the  matrix  of  experience  and  life  as  a  whole. 

The  morphology  of  thought  is  the  morphology  of  judg- 
ment. The  thought  process  is  fundamentally  a  judging 
process  —  a  process  of  being  actively  attentive,  of  being 
awake  with  reference  to  the  situation  which  we  must  meet. 
We  shall  see  that  a  judgment  is  not  an  act  distinct  from 
the  more  elaborate  processes  of  thought.  The  whole  pro- 
cess of  thought,  even  when  most  elaborate,  is  an  expansion 
and  making  definite  of  a  judgment.  Our  thinking,  in 
other  words,  is  not  chopped  up  into  parts,  but  every  devel- 
oped thought  runs  the  whole  gamut  of  the  scale  of  judg- 
ment and  inference.  Our  thinking  is  always  of  reasons, 
of  relations  to  our  former  experience — all  in  the  service  of 
the  situation  which  we  must  meet ;  and  the  upshot  of  our 
thinking  is  always  some  sort  of  a  concept  or  definition, 
which  enables  us  ever  afterwards,  in  so  far  as  it  proves  true, 
to  meet  a  similar  situation  at  sight. 

We  have  seen  that  judgment,  in  the  case  of  the  individ- 
ual, rests  on  a  background  of  habit  and  imitation,  which 
furnishes  the  mind  with  a  stock  of  adjustments,  biological 
and  ideal,  ready-made.  This  is  the  affirmative  background 
of  judgment.  Those  who  have  insisted  that  the  affirma- 
tive judgment  is  prior  to  the  negative,  have  neglected  to 


88  Truth  and  Reality 

analyze  the  real  thought  situation.  They  have  assumed 
that,  because  certain  attitudes  or  adjustments  are  presup- 
posed ;  because,  for  example,  we  have  a  stock  of  conven- 
tional propositions,  therefore  we  start  with  affirmative 
judgments.  Taking  these  cold-storage  propositions  as 
judgments,  they  have  insisted  that  the  affirmative  judgment 
comes  first,  and  that  the  negative  judgment  is  secondary  — 
an  affirmative  judgment  of  the  second  degree.  They  have 
imagined  that  the  judging  process  starts  as  a  passive  repe- 
tition of  impressions,  and  since  there  can  be  no  impressions 
corresponding  to  the  negative  judgment,  they  have  assumed 
that  the  affirmative  judgment  must  be  earlier.  But  we  have 
seen  that  we  think  only  in  the  face  of  a  problem,  in  response 
to  the  demands  of  a  situation,  whether  posited  by  the  will 
to  think,  or  whether  it  is  forced  by  the  practical  necessities 
of  life.  There  is  a  thwarting  somehow  of  the  on-going 
activity,  the  stream  of  processes  is  interrupted  with  a  call 
for  fresh  adjustment,  now  in  the  interest  of  practical  life, 
now  to  set  at  rest  theoretical  curiosity.  We  must  rule  out, 
therefore,  from  the  scope  of  judgment  such  verbal  expres- 
sions as  are  merely  a  suggestion  of  the  perceptual  or  asso- 
ciative situation  on  the  part  of  the  spectator.  The  so-called 
impersonal  judgments,  for  example,  are  usually  not  judg- 
ments at  all.  They  may  be  merely  the  result  of  verbal 
associations.  When  a  child  points  out  of  doors  toward  the 
snow  storm  and  says,  "  Snow,"  this  may  merely  mean  that 
the  perceptual  situation,  by  contiguous  association,  sug- 
gested the  word,  "snow."  We  have  judgment  only  when 
attention  attempts  actively  to  analyze  and  control  a  novel 
situation.  Where  such  analysis  and  control  is  lacking,  we 
must  resolve  the  mental  situation  into  the  proper  lower 
complexes  of  experience. 


The  Morphology  of  Truth  89 

This  being  the  case,  we  must,  contrary  to  logical  tradi- 
tion, hold  that  the  negative  judgment  is  the  earliest  form 
of  judgment.  We  wake  with  a  shock,  and  that  shock 
means  no.  "  It  won't  work."  "  It  is  not  as  expected." 
"I  am  baffled."  "This  is  different  from  the  usual." 
Such,  if  words  were  used,  would  be  the  equivalents  of 
the  first  thought  orientation.  Our  first  consciousness,  in 
the  breakdown  of  the  old  habits  or  customary  forms  of 
adjustment,  is  a  consciousness  of  no.  We  would  never 
wake  with  a  yes,  though  we  may,  once  we  are  awake, 
sustain  it  for  an  indefinite  period  in  an  organized  con- 
sciousness. In  thought,  at  least,  the  consciousness  of  non- 
being  precedes  being.  What  blinds  us  to  this  fact  is  that, 
as  a  rule,  the  judging  consciousness  presupposes  the  cus- 
tomary or  habitual  —  our  conventionalized  or  cold-storage 
judgments,  which  have  lost  their  thought  significance. 

The  thought  process,  as  such  at  any  rate,  does  not  start 
with  the  categorical  judgment.  This  is  rather  the  perch- 
ing place  of  thought  after  its  zig-zag  flight  of  deliberation. 
Once  life  is  organized,  thought  itself  may  be  interrupted  in 
this  wise ;  may  break  down  in  the  face  of  new  facts.  In 
such  a  case,  it  is  indeed  true  that  the  negative  judgment 
is  the  denial  of  a  previous  affirmative  judgment  in  our 
own  stream  of  consciousness,  though  in  this  case  we  must 
be  careful  to  distinguish  between  the  bona  fide  judgment 
of  the  individual,  and  such  beliefs  and  hypotheses  as  he 
accepts  merely  on  the  authority  of  others.  The  negative 
judgment,  in  developing  thought,  may  also  be  the  denial 
of  a  judgment  or  a  question  raised  by  some  one  else ;  but 
more  often,  it  is  a  waking  up  from  the  habitual  and  con- 
ventional, into  which  it  is  so  economic  and  so  easy  to  fall. 
Thinking  is  a  strenuous  form  of  life ;  and  unless  we  learn 


90  Truth  and  Reality 

to  take  an  athletic  enjoyment  in  it,  we  soon  drop  out 
altogether. 

We  must  distinguish  the  problem  of  the  psychological 
priority  of  judgment  from  that  of  its  logical  significance. 
Is  the  affirmative  judgment  logically  prior  to  the  negative? 
We  must  answer  that  the  two  types  are  merely  comple- 
mentary aspects  of  a  self-defining  process,  and  that  the 
question  of  priority  here  is  idle.  Judgment  means  recog- 
nizing the  differences  as  well  as  the  likenesses  of  the 
contents  selected.  All  relation  is  differentiation.  All  de- 
termination is  limitation.  In  a  world  of  pure  identity, 
thinking  would  not  be  heard  of.  We  string  our  facts,  by 
their  differences  as  well  as  their  identities,  into  classes 
and  series.  We  spread  them  out  into  a  system.  It  is 
Hegel's  immortal  merit  that  he  recognized  that  Negativi- 
tat,  significant  denial,  is  the  indispensable  backbone  of  all 
systematic  thought.  Except  for  this,  all  of  our  data  would 
be  swamped  in  an  undistinguishable  night  where  all  cows 
are  gray.  Denial  and  affirmation  are  equally  essential  to 
the  going  on  of  the  developed  thought  process.  In  system- 
atic definition,  recognizing  differences  and  their  degrees 
becomes  as  important  as  recognizing  likenesses  and  their 
degrees;  the  negative  judgment  as  important  as  the  affirm- 
ative. All  negation,  moreover,  is  with  reference  to  a  con- 
text, and  so  implies  affirmation  within  a  system.  So,  in 
turn,  affirmation  implies  negation.  As  in  the  beginning  of 
the  thought  process,  the  new  thought  consciousness  negates 
the  abstractness  of  previous  habit  and  convention,  so  in 
the  sustained  thought  process  the  larger  synthesis  negates 
the  abstract,  inadequate,  previous  generalization. 

This  does  not  mean  that  the  psychological  moment, 
which  affirms  or  denies,  recognizes  the  full  implication 


The  Morphology  of  Truth  91 

of  the  implied  affirmation  or  denial  within  the  system. 
The  moment  which  affirms  may  not  be  psychologically 
aware  of  the  implied  denial ;  and  the  moment  which  de- 
nies may  not  be  conscious  of  the  implied  affirmation.  In 
the  stream  of  thought,  it  may  require  another  moment, 
individual  or  social  —  a  critical  moment  as  superimposed 
upon  the  constructive — to  see  the  full  logical  implication 
of  the  will  attitude  as  stated.  This,  however,  is  a  question 
for  psychological  introspection  to  settle. 

Because,  within  a  significant  system,  all  affirmation 
means  exclusion  and  negation,  the  limiting  of  the  field 
of  the  possible  more  and  more  to  the  actual,  it  has  been 
maintained  that  the  judging  process  is  fundamentally  neg- 
ative, and  that  thought  proceeds  by  the  mere  destruction 
of  possibilities.  While  negation,  however,  is  fundamental 
in  the  thought  process,  we  cannot  disregard  the  positive 
consciousness  of  the  process,  the  seizing  upon  the  iden- 
tities and  constancies  in  the  midst  of  the  variety  and  flux 
of  the  process ;  for  without  the  sustained  interest  of  a  pur- 
pose which  dominates  the  process,  which  selects  and  re- 
jects, without  the  consciousness  of  the  fulfillment  of  the 
idea,  which  is  present  and  leading  throughout  the  process, 
denial  would  be  as  impossible  as  affirmation.  This  sus- 
tained and  positive  leading,  the  negative  theory  of  judg- 
ment fails  to  take  into  account. 

The  question  may  yet  be  raised,  as  to  whether  the  atti- 
tude of  the  mind  which  we  have  called  the  no  conscious- 
ness, has  objective  significance,  expresses  a  movement  of 
reality,  and  not  merely  a  subjective  movement  of  thought. 
Both  positions  have  been  taken  in  the  history  of  thought. 
Which  position  one  adopts  will  necessarily  depend  on 
one's  theory  of  reality  and  one's  conception  of  the  place 


92  Truth  and  Reality 

of  thought  in  the  final  scheme  of  things.  The  mystics 
who  look  for  reality  beyond  thought,  the  pure  empiricists 
who  look  for  reality  in  sensations,  and  the  materialists  who 
regard  reality  as  extra-mental  —  these  all  join  hands  in 
holding  that  thought  is  merely  instrumental,  and  that  re- 
ality is  something  different  from  thought,  whether  lower  or 
higher.  As  the  judging  process  itself  becomes  subjective 
in  such  theories,  the  negative  judgment,  as  such,  would  of 
course  have  nothing  corresponding  to  it  in  the  real  world. 
But  on  such  a  view,  the  affirmative  judgment,  as  little  as 
the  negative,  can  be  regarded  as  imitating  reality. 

If,  on  the  other  hand,  we  regard  reality,  with  the 
absolute  idealist,  as  awake  at  every  movement  and  at 
every  point,  —  a  complete  self-conscious  system  of 
experience,  —  then  the  process  of  negation  cannot  help 
being  regarded  as  of  ultimate  significance.  The  move- 
ment of  reality  and  the  movement  of  thought  become 
identical  in  such  a  world.  We  think  God's  thoughts  after 
him.  Our  finite  experience  imitates  point  for  point  the 
absolute  experience.  If,  however,  we  do  not  choose  to 
dogmatize  about  reality  as  a  whole,  but  modestly  take  it  as 
it  appears  in  our  finite  experience,  —  as  thinking  where  we 
must  acknowledge  it  as  thinking ;  as  non-reflective  where 
we  must  so  adjust  ourselves  to  it, — in  that  case  we  must 
hold  that  negation  is  an  objective  and  essential  factor, 
whenever  we  take  account  of  thought  as  our  object, 
wherever  we  deal  with  a  systematic  process.  And  that 
reality  thinks  in  spots  we  have  absolute  evidence  of  in  our 
thinking,  if  we  raise  the  question  at  all. 

We  have  dwelt  at  such  length  upon  the  negative  aspect 
of  the  judging  process,  because  it  reveals  the  fundamental 
unity  of  the  thought  moments  throughout  the  process  of 


The  Morphology  of  Truth  93 

judgment.  It  is  not  the  only  aspect.  With  it,  there  must 
go  the  consciousness  of  direction,  the  attempt  to  realize  a 
purpose  or  set,  however  tentative  for  the  time  being. 
Without  the  consciousness  of  a  problem,  there  could  be  no 
process  of  thought.  The  no  consciousness  with  its  sense 
of  being  baffled  is  followed  by  the  casting  about  for  means, 
the  active  analysis  of  the  situation  on  the  basis  of  a  guess 
or  hypothesis.  We  might  call  this  second  stage  in  the 
development  of  the  judging  process,  the  hypothetical 
stage.  We  try  out  various  alternatives  on  the  basis  of  our 
tentative  guesses,  which  are  continually  being  modified  as 
our  efforts  lead  toward  failure  or  success,  as  thought 
becomes  warm  in  its  search  for  its  object. 

In  using  the  adjective,  hypothetical,  to  indicate  this  trial 
stage  of  the  judging  process,  we  must  remember  that  in 
traditional  logic  the  use  of  this  term  has  been  decidedly 
ambiguous.  It  has  sometimes  been  used  to  indicate  doubt, 
and  the  effort  at  rearrangement  in  the  case  of  such  doubt, 
the  passing  from  one  equilibrium  to  another  within  the 
process  of  thought.  In  this  case  it  stands  for  the  supposi- 
Jftious  or  tentative  aspect  of  the  thought  process,  to  which 
we  have  already  referred.  But  the  term  hypothetical,  has 
also  been  used  to  indicate  the  relation  of  ground  and  con- 
sequence. And  by  virtue  of  this  use  the  hypothetical  type 
of  judgment  has  become  indistinguishable  from  the  cate- 
gorical. Of  this  latter  use  we  shall  speak  later. 

The  trial  stage  in  the  thought  process  may  take  a  more 
systematic  form  where  knowledge  is  already  organized  in 
the  given  direction  —  the  form  of  a  disjunction  of  alter- 
natives, of  an  exclusive  and  exhaustive  survey  of  possi- 
bilities, as  made  possible  in  advanced  science.  This, 
however,  is  only  an  enlargement  or  a  further  making 


94  Truth  and  Reality 

explicit  of  the  hypothetical  or  trial  stage,  which  we  have 
already  noticed.  It  is  a  recognition  of  the  complexity  of 
the  ideal  situation.  As  thought  becomes  organized,  we 
can  economize,  through  our  ideal  schematization,  the 
process  of  actual  try-out.  This  assures  greater  efficiency 
of  result.  By  analyzing  the  various  suggested  alternatives, 
we  are  more  likely  to  discover  the  relevant  leading  for 
pursuing  our  search;  and,  moreover,  the  destruction  of 
alternatives  becomes,  with  such  organization,  itself  fruitful, 
not  only  in  narrowing  the  domain  of  search,  but  in  indicat- 
ing the  direction  of  the  quarry  that  is  hunted.  This  does 
not  mean  that  we  calculate  planets  into  existence,  as  has 
sometimes  been  stated.  It  means  that  we  can  pursue  the 
simplest  and  likeliest  possibilities  first. 

The  provisional  result  which  is  attained  at  any  one  time, 
and  which  suggests  belief  and  conduct,  constitutes  the 
categorical  stage  of  the  judging  process.  The  process  of 
thought  is  circular.  It  starts,  we  have  seen,  with  nega- 
tion, or  the  need  for  fresh  adjustment,  whether  as  a  result 
of  practical  necessities  or  baffled  curiosity.  It  proceeds 
through  the  trial  stage  of  ideal  construction  and  verification, 
which  flows  out  in  advanced  knowledge  into  the  disjunc- 
tive schematization  of  alternatives.  And  its  perching 
place,  after  the  long  or  short  flight,  is  the  adopting  of  a 
provisional  scheme  for  conduct.  The  self  adjusts  itself  as 
best  it  can  to  the  new  situation,  thus  analyzed  and  made 
its  own.  The  end  of  thought  is  a  consciously  adopted 
type  of  conduct.  The  judging  process  terminates  in  a 
method  of  control  or  plan  of  procedure,  physical  or 
logical. 

This  version  of  the  thought  process  gives  us  an  intelli- 
gent idea  of  the  place  of  the  concept.  The  concept  is 


The  Morphology  of  Truth  95 

the  completed  form  of  the  categorical  judgment  at  any  stage 
of  the  history  of  thought  —  a  conscious  definition,  a  definite 
program  of  action.  There  has  been  no  end  of  confusion 
as  to  the  place  of  the  concept  in  the  treatment  of  thought 
in  the  past.  Sometimes  the  concept  has  been  identified 
with  a  substantive  word  or  term.  Sometimes  it  has  been 
identified  with  the  class  term ;  and  the  judgment  has  itself 
been  regarded  as  a  comparison  or  subordination  of  class 
terms.  Sometimes  the  concept  has  been  indentified  with 
any  abstraction  on  the  part  of  thought  or  previous  to 
thought,  in  the  way  of  quality  or  relation.  It  is  safe  to 
say  that  the  pragmatic  significance  of  the  concept  in 
modern  logic  has  been  practically  nil.  We  must  go  back 
to  Socrates,  the  inventor  of  the  concept,  for  its  true  signifi- 
cance. And  to  Socrates  the  concept  means  a  definition, 
with  its  proximate  genus  and  differentia.  The  concept 
thus  becomes  not  the  beginning  of  the  thought  process, 
but  its  terminus  —  the  description  and  identification  of  the 
situation  for  future  conduct.  The  concept  is  the  making 
definite  of  the  fringe,  of  the  tentative  leading.  The  pro- 
spective tendency  finds  its  determination  through  the  data 
which  it  must  meet.  The  centrifugal  intent  has  reached 
its  circumference  and  reflects  on  itself.  This  does  not 
mean  that  the  concept  cannot  grow.  On  the  contrary,  it 
is  made  increasingly  definite  in  the  progress  of  experience. 
It  means  that  provisionally  at  least,  as  a  halting  place  in 
the  march  of  thought,  we  have  arrived  at  a  plan  for  further 
procedure.  If  figures  were  not  misleading,  we  might  liken 
the  thought  process  to  a  spiral,  rather  than  a  circle,  for 
thought  keeps  turning  upon  itself  as  enriched  by  further 
experience. 

The  categorical  judgment,  in  turn,  just  because  it  is  the 


96  Truth  and  Reality 

settlement  of  a  case  for  the  time  being,  is  apt  to  become  a 
rule  of  thumb,  a  creed  or  formula,  and  to  be  imitated  un- 
questioningly.  It  then  ceases  to  be  a  judgment,  and  be- 
comes convention  —  thought  stereotyped  into  social  habit. 
From  this,  owing  to  the  complexity  and  changing  condi- 
tions of  life,  a  fresh  outbreak,  a  new  adaptation,  is  likely 
to  follow  with  the  same  process  of  denial,  hypothesis  and 
affirmation,  and  with  a  new  working  concept  resulting. 
This  stereotyped  or  cold-storage  judgment,  however,  into 
which  the  mind  so  easily  lapses,  is  not  to  be  taken  as  de- 
duction, as  contrasted  with  induction.  It  is  not  judgment 
at  all,  for  judgment  means  being  awake,  being  actively  in- 
terested in  the  situation.  The  cold-storage  judgment  is 
merely  a  substitute  for  thought.  The  deductive  judgment 
is  no  more  habitual  than  the  inductive.  We  may  meet  a 
novel  situation  either  deductively  or  inductively,  according 
to  the  mind's  store  of  experience.  In  either  case  we  are 
awake;  in  either  case  we  substitute  for  the  concrete  in- 
stances a  universal  or  type.  On  the  other  hand,  habit 
may  take  the  place  of  induction  as  well  as  deduction,  as 
thought  arrives  at  a  new  equilibrium.  Even  animals  some- 
times proceed  as  though  they  had  made  an  induction, 
though  acting  from  mere  instinct  or  habit. 

The  only  way  we  can  have  a  strictly  universal  categori- 
cal judgment,  is  by  isolation  and  abstraction  of  character- 
istics. It  is  in  this  way  that  science  proceeds  in  establishing 
its  so-called  laws.  Generalization,  so  long  as  we  proceed 
by  enumeration  of  instances,  must  always  be  of  a  purely 
tentative  character,  a  merely  probable  and  uncertain  guide. 
Truth  must  go  beneath  the  mere  variety  of  instances  to 
the  singling  out  of  the  constant  characteristics  which  en- 
able us  to  predict  for  the  future,  however  necessary  it  may 


The  Morphology  of  Truth  97 

be  under  our  limitations  to  act  on  incomplete  knowledge. 
There  is  strictly  no  such  thing  as  a  concrete  universal.  We 
always  buy  universality  at  the  expense  of  breaking  up  the 
concrete  fullness  of  reality,  and  dealing  with  certain  par- 
tial aspects.  Our  definitions  are  always  for  a  purpose, 
and  necessarily  leave  out  the  many  other  ways  of  taking 
reality,  which,  with  another  conative  set,  become  essential. 
We  neglect  beauty  when  our  interest  is  in  weight,  but  so 
can  we  neglect  weight  when  our  interest  is  in  beauty.  Our 
selected  universals  or  laws  are  justified,  if  we  thus  can  dip 
into  the  concrete  stream  of  experience  and  meet  its  situa- 
tions. The  statement,  all  men  are  mortal,  is  not  a  census 
of  all  men,  which  would  be  impossible,  men  being  an  indefi- 
nite quantity.  It  is  a  prediction  based  upon  certain  ab- 
stract considerations  as  regards  organic  structure,  nutrition, 
wear  and  tear,  excretion,  etc.  At  any  rate,  only  as  based 
upon  such  considerations  would  a  universal  judgment  be 
justified.  As  a  scientific  judgment,  it  stands  on  the  same 
ground  as,  all  bodies  gravitate,  which  also  pertains  to  a 
selected  characteristic  of  bodies.  Concrete  statements, 
based  upon  mere  customary  conjunction,  would  have  to  be 
treated  on  the  basis  of  probability.  And  while  the  psycho- 
logical probability  would  be  very  strong,  in  the  absence  of 
a  negative  instance,  still  no  universal  prediction  could  be 
based  upon  such  conjunction.  In  the  disjunctive  judgment 
of  chance,  the  disjunction  itself  is  based  upon  analysis  and 
abstraction  of  a  certain  constitution  of  the  object ;  and  so 
here  we  have  a  case  of  real  judgment,  however  impossible 
concrete  prediction  of  the  particular  instance  may  be. 

It  has  sometimes  been  stated  that  all  our  universal  judg- 
ments are  hypothetical.  This,  we  have  already  seen,  is 
due  to  an  ambiguity  of  language.  We  can  always  state 


98  Truth  and  Reality 

the  ground  and  consequence,  the  abstracted  characteristics 
and  our  expectations  founded  upon  them,  in  hypothetical 
form.  But  this  does  not  mean  that  our  knowledge  is  in 
this  respect  tentative  or  uncertain.  So  stating  it  is  merely 
a  trick  of  language.  It  is  precisely  in  dealing  with  these 
abstract  characters  that  we  can  make  definite  universal 
statements  about  reality.  Wherever  these  characters  re- 
peat themselves,  we  can  expect  the  same  consequences  to 
follow,  whether  in  geometry  or  in  chemistry.  Where  we 
fail  to  discover  such  identities,  we  must  be  satisfied  with 
particular  judgments  and  probabilities. 

It  must  be  clear  now  that  the  process  of  truth  is  a  pro- 
cess of  judging.  The  rest  is  machinery  in  the  service  of 
the  active  interest  which  dominates  consciousness  for  the 
time  being.  On  the  other  hand,  it  must  be  clear  that  there 
is  no  such  thing  in  thought  as  a  bare,  isolated  judgment. 
Judgment  is  always  a  process,  with  beginning,  middle  and 
end,  the  developing  of  a  drama  of  determinate  interest. 
The  traditional  names  of  judgment  we  have  found  to  be 
mere  stages,  artificially  isolated  from  this  concrete  process. 
Judgment,  inference  and  concept  again  are  not  different 
activities.  Inference  is  merely  the  expansion  of  the  judg- 
ment into  its  reasons,  machinery  in  its  realization.  And 
the  concept  is  the  provisional  halting  place  of  the  judging 
process.  What  thought  really  means  is  identification. 
We  identify  Socrates  as*a  man,  if  this  is  really  a  judgment ; 
and  then  we  proceed  to  act  toward  him  accordingly.  Better, 
if  we  had  lived  in  Athens  in  399  B.C.,  we  would  have  iden- 
tified a  certain  man  as  Socrates,  and  then  proceeded  to 
condemn  or  apotheosize  him.  We  fail  to  identify  radium 
as  one  of  the  elements,  already  labeled,  and  then  proceed  to 
find  a  new  element  by  experiment  and  isolation.  We  iden- 


The  Morphology  of  Truth  99 

tify  the  individual  situation  as  belonging  to  a  type ;  and 
then  we  adjust  ourselves  to  it  accordingly.  The  reduction 
of  life  to  types  is  the  purpose  of  thought  —  in  social  life, 
in  nature,  in  the  world  of  ideals.  This  achieved,  thought 
proceeds  with  fluency  until  the  type  itself  is  questioned. 

Induction  and  deduction  have  sometimes  been  emphasized 
as  distinct  forms  of  thought,  induction  proceeding  from  the 
particular  to  the  universal,  while  deduction  is  supposed  to 
proceed  from  the  universal  to  the  particular.  We  can  no 
longer  acquiesce  in  such  a  definition  of  induction  and  de- 
duction. The  thought  process,  in  either  case,  is  essentially 
the  same —  the  defining  of  a  particular  in  terms  of  a  con- 
text or  the  making  definite  of  a  context  in  terms  of  a 
specific  situation.  In  either  case  we  must  schematize :  we 
must  see  the  part  in  relation  to  the  whole.  The  difference 
between  induction  and  deduction  does  not  lie  in  the  ab- 
sence or  presence  of  the  universal,  but  rather  in  our  belief 
attitude  as  regards  the  universal.  In  induction  this  belief 
attitude  is  tentative,  looking  forward  for  verification.  The 
evidence  is  felt  not  to  be  all  in,  though  the  generalization 
is  by  no  means  baseless,  but  is  founded  on  analogy  and 
observed  identities  in  experience.  In  the  deductive  atti- 
tude, again,  the  feeling  is  of  the  evidence  being  in,  of 
definite  action  now  being  possible.  The  attitude  is  retro- 
spective as  regards  confirmation,  but  prospective  as  re- 
gards conduct  or  the  fulfillment  of  the  specific  conative 
tendency.  In  deduction,  we  identify  the  situation  as  be- 
longing to  a  type,  and  proceed  to  act  accordingly.  In  in- 
duction, we  suggest  the  type  to  which  the  situation  may 
belong,  and  proceed  to  try  out  our  suggestion.  Psycholog- 
ically, we  may  say  that  the  consciousness  is  the  reversal 
of  that  stated  in  traditional  logic.  In  deduction  we  have 


ioo  Truth  and  Reality 

the  consciousness  of  going  from  the  particular  to  the 
implied  universal,  while  in  induction  we  suggest  a  universal 
for  the  particular,  i.e.,  the  emphasis  in  deduction  is  on  the 
new  instance,  in  induction  on  the  new  universal.  In  either 
case,  we  confront  a  novel  situation  in  terms  of  a  universal 
or  type.  If  in  induction  we  may  be  mistaken  as  to  the 
guiding  universal,  so  in  deduction  we  may  be  mistaken  in 
identifying  the  new  instance  with  a  well-known  type. 
Both  attitudes  must  be  open  to  revision  in  further  experi- 
ence. Only  as  this  active  consciousness  of  relation  to  a 
context,  with  its  reasons,  is  maintained,  do  we  have  thought 
at  all.  And  this  is  equally  characteristic  of  deduction  as 
of  induction. 

As  the  real  problem  of  thought  is  the  identifying  of  an 
instance  as  belonging  to  a  type,  so  the  real  and  only  re- 
quirement of  thought  is  what  logic  has  called  distribution 
—  the  distinct  isolation  in  thought,  if  not  physically,  of  the 
relevant  character  from  the  complex  situations  in  which  we 
find  it.  This  is  the  discovery  of  the  middle  term.  And 
this  is  equally  important  in  concrete  induction,  where  we 
deal  with  perceptions,  as  in  formal  deduction,  where  our 
facts  are  ready-made  propositions.  In  each  case,  logic 
has  laid  down  certain  technical  rules  or  precautions  for 
distinguishing  this  middle  term.  In  formal  logic,  we 
have  an  organized  technic  called  the  syllogism,  with  its 
canons  for  testing  this  identity  as  implied  in  the  linguistic 
form  of  the  argument.  We  must  make  sure  that  we  have 
real  identity  of  content  and  that  we  take  this  identity  in  no 
other  way  than  as  indicated  in  the  data  —  the  propositions 
which  we  have  set  ourselves  to  analyze.  In  the  case  of 
concrete  induction,  we  have  found  that  we  cannot  establish 
a  thread  of  identity  in  the  many  instances  by  merely  taking 


The  Morphology  of  Truth  101 

account  of  agreement.  We  must  also  take  into  account 
the  negative  instances,  through  supplementing  the  method 
of  agreement  with  the  method  of  difference,  the  combined 
method  of  agreement  and  difference,  the  method  of  concomi- 
tant variation,  and  the  various  statistical  methods  which 
we  must  use  in  dealing  with  the  more  complex  masses  of 
facts.  But  everywhere  the  object  of  this  technic  is  the 
distributing  of  the  middle  term,  «>.,  making  the  identity  or 
universal  clear  and  distinct.  This  is  the  only  requirement 
of  thought.  This  does  not  mean  that  we  talk  syllogisms, 
or  consciously  think  in  the  forms  of  the  syllogism.  This 
is  only  the  diagram  or  schema  for  exhibiting  the  relations 
as  implied  in  thinking.  The  order  of  the  premises  in  the 
syllogism  is  due  to  our  convenience  for  exhibiting  these 
relations  and  need  not  coincide  with  the  order  in  actual 
thinking.  Moreover,  in  actual  thought,  we  seldom  express 
the  full  implications  of  our  reasoning.  Ordinarily  certain 
general  assumptions  remain  unstated  as  obvious  for  the 
particular  procedure.  And  ordinarily  we  need  not  stop  to 
draw  the  formal  conclusion.  It  has  been  said  that  the  con- 
clusion overshadows  psychologically  the  premises.  This  is 
not  generally  true.  The  pivot  of  our  thinking  is  the  so- 
called  minor  premise,  the  identification  of  the  new  situation 
with  a  type.  Newton  identifies  the  falling  moon  with  the 
generalizations  already  attained  by  Galileo  as  regards  fall- 
ing terrestrial  bodies.  But  probably  the  tentative  conduct 
in  the  way  of  equations  followed  immediately  upon  the 
suggested  identification  of  the  type.  The  cashier  at  the 
window  identifies  his  customer  as  belonging  to  a  type,  and 
regulates  his  conduct  accordingly  without  formulating  the 
major  premise  or  conclusion.  The  policeman  identifies  a 
certain  man  as  a  dangerous  criminal  and  proceeds  to  arrest 


IO2  Truth  and  Reality 

him.  He  does  not  argue  in  full :  All  criminals  should  be 
arrested ;  this  man  is  a  criminal,  therefore  he  should  be 
arrested.  Action  takes  the  place  of  the  formal  conclusion, 
and  the  major  premise  is  taken  for  granted. 

While  this  is  true,  while  the  identification  of  a  type  is 
the  essential  aspect  of  reasoning,  we  can,  whenever  we  so 
choose,  supply  the  larger  context  presupposed  in  the  argu- 
ment ;  and  we  can  also  draw  the  conclusion  which  is  implied 
in  our  procedure.  The  cases  in  which  it  has  been  main- 
tained that  the  syllogism  is  not  applicable  —  such  cases  as 
involve  space  and  time  relations  and  quantitative  compari- 
son—  will  be  found  to  be  cases  where  the  major  premise 
has  not  been  stated.  Certain  presuppositions,  as  regards 
the  nature  of  space  relations  and  time  relations  and  of 
the  abstract  postulates  of  quantitative  comparison,  are  as 
a  matter  of  fact  implied  in  our  judgment,  and  can  be  made 
explicit,  though  it  is  generally  superfluous  to  do  so.  All 
arguments,  inductive  and  deductive,  in  so  far  as  resolvable 
into  language,  are  statable  in  the  syllogistic  form,  if  we 
care  so  to  state  them.  In  any  case,  we  get  out  of  the 
syllogism  only  what  we  put  in ;  and  if  we  put  in  probabil- 
ity, we  can  draw  only  probability. 

It  has  been  stated  by  recent  psychology  *  that  the  truth 
of  a  proposition  rests  upon  its  being  believed,  that  the  ul- 
timate test  of  truth  is  that  some  one  believes,  and  that  the 
task  of  assuring  the  truth  of  a  statement  is  the  task  of 
making  the  individuals  concerned  believe  the  proposition 
that  one  is  endeavoring  to  establish.  This  confusion  of 
the  basis  of  belief  with  the  basis  of  validity  seems  a  re- 
gretable  result  of  the  patronizing  manner  with  which  recent 

1  This  is  the  impression  I  get  from  a  thoughtful  book  by  Professor  Pillsbury, 
"The  Psychology  of  Reasoning."  See  especially  pp.  205  and  231. 


The  Morphology  of  Truth  103 

psychology  has  treated  elementary  logic.  Since  Aristotle, 
formal  logic,  for  which  contemporary  psychology  has 
such  contempt,  not  only  has  recognized  the  difference  be- 
tween being  believed  and  being  valid,  but  has  reduced  to 
technic  the  various  fallacies  which  are  due  to  belief. 
Such  reasons  for  false  belief  may  lie  in  lack  of  sagacity 
in  discerning  the  relevant  middle  term ;  in  the  confusion 
due  to  the  ambiguity  of  language,  which  sometimes  gives 
us  the  identity  of  a  word  instead  of  identity  of  content ; 
in  the  bias  of  our  training  as  a  result  of  past  prejudices 
and  traditions ;  in  our  own  emotions  and  temperament ;  in 
faulty  observations,  such  as  the  emphasis  of  the  affirma- 
tive instances,  and  the  neglect  of  the  negative ;  in  the  dis- 
traction of  the  attention  from  the  real  issue  by  a  mass  of 
verbiage  and  irrational  appeal ;  in  the  substitution  of  mere 
psychological  sequence  for  causal  connection,  etc.,  etc.  It  is 
true  that  truth  coerces  belief ;  but  it  is  far  from  true  that 
belief,  however  strong  for  the  time  being,  can  make  things 
so,  unless  belief  itself  creates  its  own  facts. 

There  need  be  no  relation  between  the  grounds  of  belief 
and  the  grounds  of  truth.  Belief  looks  backward  to  the 
past,  to  our  temperamental  and  social  heritage,  our  psy- 
chological associations,  to  custom  and  habit.  Truth  looks 
forward  to  consequences,  to  correspondences,  to  conduct. 
Whatever  our  beliefs  may  be,  that  is  true  which  terminates 
in  the  intended  facts.  Hence  the  dogmatism  of  faith,  on 
the  one  hand,  and  the  necessary  open-mindedness,  humility 
and  tolerance  of  the  real  truth  seeker,  on  the  other.  How- 
ever prone  belief  is  to  close  the  accounts,  the  investigator 
knows  that  the  full  truth  lies  in  the  future  and  that  he 
must  take  as  provisional  his  fragmentary  insight. 


CHAPTER  VI 
THE  CONTENT  OF  TRUTH 

LOCKE,  in  classifying  the  operations  of  the  mind  with  ref- 
erence to  its  content,  has  shown  that  three  different  types 
of  activity  are  involved — the  activity  of  compounding,  which 
gives  us  our  various  complex  ideas,  including  substances ; 
the  activity  of  relating,  which  arranges  our  contents  side  by 
side  and  observes  their  likenesses  and  differences,  as  well  as 
other  relations ;  and  the  activity  of  separating  which  gives  us 
our  abstract  ideas,  which  are  so  important  for  descriptive 
purposes.  Now  Locke  rightly  points  out  that  the  process 
of  truth  has  to  do  with  the  second  type  of  activity.  It  is  a 
process  of  relating,  or  as  he  himself  puts  it :  "  Knowledge 
seems  to  me  to  be  nothing  but  the  perception  of  connection 
and  agreement,  or  disagreement  and  repugnancy  of  any  of 
our  ideas." 1  This  agreement  according  to  Locke  is  four- 
fold. It  concerns  identity  or  diversity,  which  means,  "  to 
know  each  what  it  is,  and  thereby  also  to  perceive  their 
difference,  and  that  one  is  not  another."  It  concerns  re- 
lations, in  a  limited  sense,  viz.,  "  in  several  ways  the  mind 
takes  of  comparing"  its  ideas.  It  concerns  further  the  co- 
existence of  ideas  in  the  same  subject,  or  that  one  idea 
always  accompanies  or  is  joined  with  certain  other  ideas. 
And  it  concerns  lastly  the  agreeing  of  any  idea  with  actual 
or  real  existence.  "  Thus  blue  is  not  yellow,  is  of  identity. 
Two  triangles  upon  equal  bases  between  two  parallels  are 

1  "  An  Essay  concerning  Human  Understanding,"  Bk.  IV,  Ch.  I,  §  2. 

104 


The  Content  of  Truth  105 

equal,  is  of  relation.  Iron  is  susceptible  of  magnetic  im- 
pressions, is  of  coexistence.  God  is,  is  of  real  existence."  * 
Locke  realizes,  however,  that  all  these  cases  of  agreement 
are  merely  different  relations  between  the  contents  of  our 
experience,  and  defines  actual  knowledge,  as  opposed  to 
what  he  calls  "habitual,"  or  what  James  would  call  "cold- 
storage,"  knowledge,  as  "the  present  view,  the  mind  has 
of  the  agreement  or  disagreement  of  any  of  its  ideas,  or  of 
the  relation  they  have  one  to  another." 

Locke's  whole  scheme  of  knowledge  is  beautifully  worked 
out  on  the  basis  of  this  theory  of  relations.  "  The  degrees 
of  our  knowledge,"  for  example,  depend  upon  our  mode  of 
discerning  these  relations  of  the  contents  of  experience. 
The  mind  may  immediately  intuit  the  agreement  or  dis- 
agreement of  two  ideas,  without  the  intervention  of  any 
other,  which  is  the  most  certain  kind  of  knowledge.  As 
Locke  puts  it:  "This  part  of  knowledge  is  irresistible, 
and,  like  bright  sunshine,  forces  itself  immediately  to  be 
perceived,  as  soon  as  ever  the  mind  turns  its  view  that 
way."2  Moreover,  "it  is  on  this  intuition  that  depends  all 
the  certainty  and  evidence  of  all  our  knowledge,"  for  "  this 
intuition  is  necessary  in  all  the  connections  of  intermediate 
ideas."  Less  certain  is  demonstrative  knowledge,  "where 
the  mind  perceives  the  agreement  or  disagreement  of  ideas, 
not  immediately,"  but  by  the  intervention  of  other  ideas,  as 
in  the  case  of  the  equality  of  the  three  angles  of  a  triangle 
to  two  right  angles.3  Least  certain  is  sensitive  knowledge 
which  has  to  do  with  the  "perception  of  the  mind  employed 
about  the  particular  existence  of  finite  beings  about  us." 
When  again  he  takes  up  "  the  extent  of  our  knowledge,"  he 
easily  makes  clear  that  knowledge  can  extend  no  farther 
1  /«</.,  §  7.  3  Ibid.,  Ch.  II,  §  i.  »  Ibid.t  §  2. 


io6  Truth  and  Reality 

than  we  have  ideas  and  can  perceive  the  agreement  or 
disagreement  of  such  ideas.1  When  further  he  takes  up 
"  the  reality  of  our  knowledge,"  he  shows  with  the  same 
clearness  that  our  knowledge  is  real  just  in  so  far  as  our 
ideas  terminate  in  the  intended  facts,  whether  those  be  our 
own  complex  ideas,  or  our  immediate  experiences  of  things.2 
While  our  knowledge  of  real  substances  is  limited,  yet  here 
too  "  our  complex  ideas  of  them  must  be  such,  and  such 
only,  as  are  made  up  of  such  simple  ones,  as  have  been 
discovered  to  coexist  in  Nature."  In  any  case,  "whatever 
ideas  we  have,  the  agreement  they  finally  have  with  others 
will  still  be  knowledge." 

Speaking  now  in  terms  of  judgment,  we  must  hold  that 
the  judging  process  cannot  be  stated  in  terms  of  attitude 
alone.  We  must  also  take  into  account  the  relations  of 
the  content.  The  judgment,  in  other  words,  involves  two 
things.  It  involves,  on  the  side  of  the  will,  a  specific  atti- 
tude or  set.  It  involves,  on  the  side  of  the  content,  cer- 
tain relations  which  the  judging  process  must  imitate.  It 
is  impossible  to  define  judgment,  either  purely  in  terms  of 
attitude,  on  the  one  hand,  or  merely  in  terms  of  content 
on  the  other.  This  has  been  the  mistake  in  many  of  the 
past  theories  of  judgment.  Judgment  is  a  certain  set 
towards  certain  content  relations.  We  are  here  concerned, 
however,  not  with  the  set,  but  with  the  relational  content 
of  the  judging  process.  If  judgment  subjectively  means 
being  awake,  sustained  attention,  we  must  also  define  the 
nature  of  its  content.  Awake  about  what?  Sustained 
attention  to  what  ?  It  is  being  awake  with  reference  to 
specific  content  relations  or  content  complexity,  which  it 

1  "  An  Essay  concerning  Human  Understanding,"  Bk.  IV,  Ch.  Ill,  §  2. 
*  Ibid.,  Ch.  IV. 


The  Content  of  Truth  107 

aims  to  copy,  that  makes  judgments  true  or  false,  and  which 
distinguishes  judgment  from  the  mere  association  of  ideas. 
"The  judgment,"  as  Russell  puts  it,  "is  true  when  there  is 
such  a  complex,  and  false  when  there  is  not."1  Or,  as 
Locke  long  ago  put  it :  "  Truth,  then,  seems  to  me,  in  the 
proper  import  of  the  word,  to  signify  nothing  but  the  join- 
ing or  separating  of  signs,  as  the  things  signified  by  them 
do  agree  or  disagree  one  with  another."  2 

Before  treating  of  the  epistemological  significance  of  the 
relational  consciousness,  I  wish  to  say  a  few  words  as  regards 
the  psychological  analysis  of  the  problem.  Are  there,  on 
the  side  of  consciousness,  feelings  of  relation  of  a  unique 
kind  ?  Or  are  these  feelings  of  relations  reducible  to  sen- 
sations ?  Is  our  consciousness  of  likeness  and  difference, 
of  side  by  side,  of  before  and  after,  of  cause  and  effect,  of 
significant  meaning,  reducible  to  mere  sensations  in  the  head 
or  throat  ?  Is  the  consciousness  of  the  activity  of  thought, 
in  short,  reducible  to  kinesthetic  images  and  sensations  ? 

It  seems  to  me  that  those  who  analyze  relational  con- 
sciousness into  kinesthetic  images  and  sensations  confuse 
the  physiological  concomitants  and  their  sensations  with  the 
nature  of  the  thought  process  itself.  The  sensations  and 
images  do  not  constitute  the  intent — the  sense  of  fitness, 
the  fringe  of  meaning  —  of  the  thought  process,  whether 
such  sensations  are  present  or  not.  We  cannot  interpolate 
them  into  the  thought  process.  They  vary  independently 
of  the  intent,  all  the  way  from  focal  prominence  to  zero. 
They  may  exist  in  all  sorts  of  forms,  when  they  are  present, 
without  relevance  to  the  on-going  of  the  thought  process. 
It  seems  to  me  as  if  Titchener  and  others  had  made  the 

1  Russell,  "  Philosophical  Essays,'  p.  184. 

*  Locke,  "  An  Essay  concerning  Human  Understanding,"  Bk.  IV,  Ch.  V,  §  3. 


io8  Truth  and  Reality 

same  mistake  with  regard  to  our  feelings  of  relation  that 
James  made  in  regard  to  mental  activity  in  general.  They 
have  substituted  physiological  symptoms,  with  their  con- 
comitant sensations,  for  the  nature  of  the  process  with  its 
definite  consciousness  of  direction. 

In  a  similar  manner,  we  cannot  define  this  intent  of 
thought  in  terms  of  a  static  context  of  ideas  and  sensa- 
tions. Rather,  it  is  a  dynamic  will,  with  its  definite  set, 
controlling  and  selecting  relevant  contents,  which  gives  the 
process  this  unique  feeling  for  fitness,  this  sense  of  wel- 
come or  rejection,  this  sense  of  meaning.  This  dynamic 
leading,  corresponding  to  the  whole  movement  of  thought, 
the  structural  psychologist,  with  his  abstract  atomism,  has 
lost  sight  of.  To  me,  at  any  rate,  the  thought-set  or  intent 
is  a  unique  fact,  a  specific  content  not  reducible  to  sensa- 
tions. It  makes  a  difference  whether  sensations  are  the 
contents  of  thought  or  merely  the  symptoms  or  concomi- 
tants of  thought.  The  kinesthetic  images  and  sensations 
seem  to  me  to  be  the  latter. 

If  we  address  ourselves  now  to  the  epistemological  sig- 
nificance of  the  relational  content  of  consciousness,  we  must 
face  the  question  whether  these  relations  are  to  be  taken 
as  internal  relations  or  external  relations.  Do  the  rela- 
tions depend  upon  the  nature  of  their  terms  —  being,  there- 
fore, uniquely  determined  within  a  total  inclusive  system  of 
significance ;  or  are  relations  external  to  the  natures  of  the 
terms,  and  can  other  terms  be  substituted  without  chang- 
ing the  relations  and  vice  versa  ?  As  Russell  defines  exter- 
nal relations :  "  The  term  A  may  have  a  relation  to  a  term 
B,  without  there  being  any  constituent  of  A,  corresponding 
to  this  relation." 1  This  problem  of  internal  and  external 

ljeur.  Phil.  Psych,  and  Sri.  Mcth.,  Vol.  VIII,  p.  159. 


The  Content  of  Truth  109 

relations  may  be  taken  in  two  ways.  It  may  be  taken  as 
having  to  do  with  objective  or  content  relations,  or  it  may 
be  taken  as  having  to  do  with  the  relation  of  knower  to 
known.  The  problem  in  either  case  is  the  same :  Is  the 
content  uniquely  determined  by  its  context,  or  can  it  be 
taken  as  figuring  indifferently  in  a  number  of  contexts? 
Can  any  part  of  experience  be  exchanged,  or  does  it  adhere 
to  its  context  in  such  a  way  that  it  alone  can  fulfill  the 
demands  of  the  specific  whole  ? 

Both  of  these  positions  have  been  taken  and  worked  out 
to  their  extreme  consequences.  Absolute  idealism  insists 
upon  internal  relations,  neo-realism  upon  external  relations. 
According  to  absolute  idealism,  every  fact  belongs  to  a 
system,  its  nature  implies  the  system.  We  cannot  under- 
stand any  part  of  the  universe,  root  and  all,  without 
following  out  its  implications  in  the  whole,  nor  can  we  under- 
stand the  whole,  except  in  terms  of  its  interwoven  parts. 
It  is  only  the  abstract  symbols,  such  as  we  use  in  mathe- 
matics or  language,  which  are  exchangeable.  The  real 
contents  themselves  are  uniquely  determined.  As  put  by 
Royce : l  "  There  is  an  absolute  experience  for  which  the 
conception  of  an  absolute  reality,  that  is,  the  conception  of 
a  system  of  ideal  truth,  is  fulfilled  by  the  very  contents 
that  get  presented  to  this  Experience.  This  absolute  ex- 
perience is  related  to  our  experience  as  an  Organic  Whole 
to  its  own  fragments.  It  is  an  experience  which  finds  ful- 
filled all  that  the  completest  thought  can  rationally  conceive 
as  genuinely  possible.  Herein  lies  its  definition  as  an  Ab- 
solute. For  the  Absolute  Experience  as  for  ours,  there 
are  data,  contents,  facts.  But  these  data,  these  contents, 
express,  for  the  Absolute  Experience,  its  own  meaning,  its 

1  "  The  Conception  of  God,"  pp.  43-44. 


no  Truth  and  Reality 

thought,  its  ideas.  Contents  beyond  these  that  it  possesses, 
the  Absolute  Experience  knows  to  be,  in  genuine  truth,  im- 
possible. Hence  its  contents  are  indeed  particular,  —  a 
selection  from  the  world  of  bare  or  merely  conceptual  pos- 
sibilities,—  but  they  form  a  self-determined  whole,  than 
which  nothing  completer,  more  organic,  more  fulfilling, 
more  transparent,  or  more  complete  in  meaning,  is  con- 
cretely or  genuinely  possible.  On  the  other  hand,  these 
contents  are  not  foreign  to  those  of  our  finite  experience, 
but  are  inclusive  of  them  in  the  unity  of  one  life."  The 
same  position  has  been  stated  by  Joachim,  bringing  out 
its  negative  as  well  as  its  positive  implication.1  "  Truth,  we 
said,  was  the  systematic  coherence  which  characterized  a 
significant  whole.  And  we  proceeded  to  identify  a  signifi- 
cant whole  with  '  an  organized  individual  experience,  self- 
fulfilling  and  self -fulfilled.'  Now  there  can  be  one  and  only 
one  such  experience:  or  only  one  significant  whole,  the 
significance  of  which  is  self-contained  in  the  sense  required. 
For  it  is  absolute  self-fulfillment,  absolutely  self-contained 
significance,  that  is  postulated ;  and  nothing  short  of  abso- 
lute individuality  —  nothing  short  of  the  completely  whole 
experience  —  can  satisfy  this  postulate.  And  human 
knowledge  —  not  merely  my  knowledge  or  yours,  but  the 
best  and  fullest  knowledge  in  the  world  at  any  stage  of  its 
development  —  is  clearly  not  a  significant  whole  in  this 
ideally  complete  sense.  Hence  the  truth,  which  our  sketch 
described,  is  —  from  the  point  of  view  of  human  intelli- 
gence—  an  Ideal,  and  an  Ideal  which  can  never  as  such, 
or  in  its  completeness,  be  actual  as  human  experience." 

If  we  state   the   problem  from  the  subjective  point  of 
view  —  the  reading  of  the  universe  in  terms  of  the  impli- 

lMThe  Nature  of  Truth,"  Oxford,  1906,  p.  78. 


The  Content  of  Truth  III 

cation  of  our  own  subjective  meaning  —  knowing  reality 
becomes  merely  a  question  of  knowing  what  we  mean. 
The  difference  between  internal  and  external,  from  the 
point  of  view  of  epistemological  idealism,  is  purely  a 
relative  one.  What  seems  external  is  merely  so  because 
of  our  failure  to  know  our  own  real  meaning.  Our  mean- 
ing, in  other  words,  is  part  of  a  systematic  whole,  reveals 
this  whole  point  for  point,  if  we  only  become  completely 
conscious  of  our  own  meaning.  Knowledge  is  thus  the 
passing  from  a  confused  consciousness  to  a  clear  and  dis- 
tinct* consciousness  of  our  own  experience.  The  finite 
self,  like  Leibniz's  monad,  in  knowing  itself,  knows  the 
universe.  It  matters  not,  then,  where  you  start,  whether 
you  start  with  your  subjective  meaning,  or  some  one  else's 
meaning,  or  with  a  fragment  of  nature;  the  dialectic 
of  experience  will  bring  you  face  to  face  with  the  com- 
pletely organized  and  self-revealing  experience  of  the  uni- 
verse. 

If  you  object  to  the  monotony  and  lack  of  variety  and 
contingency  in  such  an  idealistic  world,  the  absolute 
idealist  has  no  difficulty  in  pointing  you  to  types  of  ideal 
universes  which  present  all  the  elements  of  fascination 
and  discovery  that  thought  could  ask.  Take  for  example 
the  ideal  universe  of  number.  While  it  is  true  that  every 
part  of  the  number  system,  rational  or  irrational,  is  deter- 
mined by  the  concept  of  number,  it  is  also  true  that  in  this 
ideal  constitution,  the  particular  numbers  possess  their  own 
unique  and  individual  significance  which  cannot  be  read 
off  a  priori,  but  must  be  ascertained  by  actual  discov- 
ery in  the  course  of  experience.  Here  individuality  and 
contingency  exist  as  aspects  within  the  self-consistent 
and  determined  whole  of  thought.  And  what  is  true  of 


112  Truth  and  Reality 

number,  in  the  small,  is  true  of  the  entire  universe,  or  reality 
in  the  large. 

Now,  in  the  first  place,  there  is  nothing  contradictory  in 
such  a  conception  of  internal  relations.  We  are  familiar 
with  such  internal  relations,  involving  the  nature  of  the 
parts,  in  every  teleological  whole ;  and  that  there  are  such 
significant  wholes,  we  all  must  admit.  In  a  logical  system, 
for  example,  such  as  geometry,  the  parts  clearly  depend 
upon  the  sort  of  whole  which  we  have  postulated.  One 
part  of  the  syllogism  points  to  the  rest,  and  we  can  re- 
construct the  other  parts  from  it.  A  fragment  of  a  statue 
or  other  work  of  art,  points  to  a  completion  which  we  can 
at  least  schematically  indicate,  even  though  filling  out  the 
complete  context  involves  other  unique  relations  which  can- 
not be  construed  a  priori.  The  Winged  Victory  plainly  in- 
dicates its  fragmentary  character  to  the  imagination,  even 
though  no  artist  dares  complete  the  actual  marble.  The 
femur  of  an  extinct  species  indicates  to  the  paleontologist 
the  general  structure  of  the  animal  in  question.  Words  in 
discourse  cannot  be  shuffled  at  random.  The  word  belongs 
in  its  context.  If  we  cannot  conceive  internal  relations, 
the  interpenetration  of  parts  in  the  fulfillment  of  a  pur- 
pose, all  teleological  constructions  become  impossible.  It 
is  not  true  within  a  teleological  whole  that  parts  can  be 
exchanged  indifferently  to  their  relations.  You  cannot  sub- 
stitute the  head  for  the  hand  within  an  organism,  or  the 
beginning  for  the  end  of  the  drama.  The  parts  plainly  indi- 
cate that  they  belong  together  and  are  uniquely  determined 
by  their  relations  to  the  whole. 

The  relation  of  whole  and  part  comes  to  seem  contra- 
dictory only  when  we  verbalize  the  relations,  and  substitute 
our  intellectual  abstractions  for  the  specific  fulfillment  of 


The  Content  of  Truth  113 

the  will  with  which  we  started.  We  must  always  remem- 
ber that  thought  is  not  another  compartment  of  expe- 
rience, distinct  from  will,  but  thought  is  will  articulated, 
awake  as  to  its  intent  and  organization;  and  our  being 
awake  as  to  the  completeness  of  the  fulfillment  of  the  will, 
in  its  complexity  of  parts,  as  in  the  tonal  unity  of  a  melody, 
does  not  disrupt  the  whole  or  make  it  the  less  a  whole. 
Nor  does  it  follow  because  the  parts  of  the  whole  have 
internal  relations,  that  they  are  exhausted  in  these  relations. 
The  parts  have  individuality,  too.  The  tone  has  its  in- 
dividual character,  though  it  blends  into  a  larger  melody. 
Each  number  is  an  individual  as  well  as  a  member  of  a 
system.  The  judgment  while  it  is  part  of  the  argument 
also  has  reality  as  judgment.  In  all  such  teleological  cases, 
it  is  plain  that  the  part  implies  the  whole,  and  the  whole 
implies  the  part.  This  implication  does  not  mean  mere 
numerical  taking  or  spatial  juxtaposition.  Rather  it  is 
the  fulfillment  of  a  specific,  self-realizing  will.  Neither 
parts  nor  whole  exist  as  such,  except  as  the  embodiment  or 
positing  of  a  will.  It  is  the  will  which  frames  wholes  and 
which  demarcates  parts  within  wholes  according  to  its 
interest  and  emphasis.  We  may  regard  the  part  as  a  func- 
tion of  the  system  or  the  system  as  the  unity  of  parts.  But 
this  is  merely  a  question  of  the  limitation  of  our  attention. 
Neither  exists  except  as  the  embodiment  of  a  unique  will. 
Neither  parts  nor  wholes  exist  as  pure  abstractions  which 
are  quantitatively  comparable. 

If  we  assume,  on  the  other  hand,  that  the  teleological 
relation  of  whole  and  part  is  contradictory,  and  if  truth 
necessarily  implies  such  internal  relationship,  this  objection 
would  destroy  not  only  the  idealistic  theory  of  truth,  but 
all  possibility  of  truth.  For  whatever  may  be  the  relation 


114  Truth  and  Reality 

of  truth  to  its  object,  truth  itself  as  a  system  of  judgments 
is  a  teleological  unity  of  parts.  But  the  supposed  truth 
that  all  truth  is  contradictory,  is  self-refuting  and  does  not 
prove  the  impossibility  of  truth,  but  the  absurdity  of  a  cer- 
tain theory  of  truth.  I  do  not  see  a  priori  why  a  context 
cannot  be  systematically  conscious  of  itself  without  contra- 
diction ;  or  why  we  should  not  logically  take  account  of, 
as  well  as  appreciate,  any  teleological  whole  —  its  internal 
relations,  its  fitness  of  parts,  its  significant  unity.  And 
there  is  no  need  of  supposing  that  this  taking  over  of  the 
relations  in  individual  consciousness  in  any  wise  disrupts 
the  unity  or  makes  the  context  contradictory.  Whenever 
internal  unity  exists,  whether  esthetic  or  ethical  or  logical, 
there  thought  can  as  truly  trace  this  unity  from  part  to 
part.  A  work  of  art  can  be  understood  as  well  as  appre- 
ciated. It  is  constructed  according  to  certain  principles, 
which  can  be  grasped  a  posteriori  at  any  rate,  as  we  always 
have  to  grasp  the  concrete,  however  different  the  attitude 
of  understanding  is  from  that  of  appreciation.  What  we 
grasp  in  taking  account  of  the  unity  of  the  object  is  not 
the  attitude,  but  the  character  of  the  content.  The  attitude 
of  the  spectator  does  not  make  the  unity  in  art  any  more 
than  in  science.  The  unity  in  either  case  must  be  implied 
in  the  content  as  well  as  apprehended  by  the  will. 

-       f 

What  halve  realism  has  had  in  mind,  doubtless,  is  that  we 
can  abstract  contents  from  their  contexts,  the  qualities  from 
the  thing,  the  relations  from  the  parts.  Having  thus  ab- 
stracted them,  we  can  regard  them  as  independent  entities 
and  treat  the  relations  as  external  and  indifferent  to  the 
terms  and  the  terms  to  the  relations.  But  however  conven- 
ient such  abstractions  may  be  for  certain  descriptive  and 
practical  purposes,  qualities  and  relations  only  exist  as  taken 


The  Content  of  Truth  115 

in  contexts.  And  in  significant  contexts,  contents  and  re- 
lations no  longer  stand  out  as  separate  entities,  but  the 
contents  themselves  suggest  the  ideal  relations.  The  con- 
tents have  their  own  significance  as  molded  by  the  will  into 
ideal  unity.  The  distinction  between  contents  and  rela- 
tions becomes  here  a  merely  relative  one,  —  one  of  psycho- 
logical emphasis. 

It  has  been  urged  that  as  regards  religious  objects  we 
have  a  different  case,  and  that  here,  at  any  rate,  the  unity 
is  merely  subjective.  But  this  again  is  due  to  confusion  in 
the  use  of  terms.  The  unity  of  the  religious  content  is  no 
more  subjective  in  the  sense  of  being  due  to  our  apprehend- 
ing it,  to  our  understanding  or  appreciating  it,  than  the 
unity  of  the  scientific  or  esthetic  object.  The  content  of 
the  religious  experience  is  clearly  organized.  It  points  to  a 
unity  of  its  own,  it  fulfills  a  will.  It  is  true  that  the  belief 
in  the  objective  reality  of  this  unity  involves  an  element  of 
risk,  not  involved  in  the  finite  perceptual  object,  but  this  is 
another  story  and  must  be  tested  in  its  own  way.  The 
Homeric  Zeus  may  have  no  objective  existence,  indepen- 
dent of  our  finite  minds,  yet  he  possesses,  for  all  that,  unity 
of  content,  independent  of  our  individual  apprehension. 

It  has  been  maintained,  as  against  absolute  idealism,  that 
absolute  truth  is  unattainable,  and  even  some  champions 
of  absolute  idealism  have  admitted  this  paradox.  But  in 
any  case  this  objection  cannot  be  aimed  exclusively  at  abso- 
lute idealism.  It  would  be  as  much  of  an  objection  against 
any  other  theory  of  the  universe,  for  truth  always  aims  at 
completeness.  As  a  matter  of  fact  such  an  objection  is 
more  dogmatic  than  real.  We  cannot  say  a  priori  that 
complete  truth  is  unattainable.  The  play  upon  the  phrase 
infinite  truth  is  merely  a  rhetorical  way  of  expressing  our 


n6  Truth  and  Reality 

aiming  at  complete  truth.  This  is  the  implied  end  of  all 
research,  whether  metaphysical  or  scientific. 

To  disprove  the  idealistic  assumption  of  a  completely 
organized  truth  by  the  counter  assumption  that  there  are 
independent  parts  of  truth  is  merely  begging  the  question. 
No  one  disputes  that  part-truths  are  true  for  a  partial  pur- 
pose. For  ordinary  purposes  we  can  take  2  +  2  =  4  as  an 
independent  system,  ignoring  its  larger  implications.  But 
is  there  not  implied,  after  all,  a  larger  system  —  a  constitu- 
tion of  number  of  which  this  equation  is  a  part,  and  to  which 
it  owes  its  existence  ?  And  does  not  number  in  turn  imply 
a  certain  constitution  of  thought  ?  This  again  may  imply 
a  certain  constitution  of  reality  as  a  whole  without  a  pri- 
ori contradiction.  Is  not  the  separateness  of  the  system 
2  +  2  =  4  due  primarily  to  our  limitations  of  attention  ? 

So  far,  finally,  as  the  question  regarding  the  possibility 
of  error  is  concerned,  error  implies  at  least  a  definite 
epistemological  universe,  whether  this  must  be  taken  as 
existential  or  not.  In  a  world  of  mere  chance,  error  would 
be  as  meaningless  as  truth.  Each  implies  certain  postu- 
lates, a  definite  constitution.  True,  it  is  difficult,  on  the 
theory  of  absolute  idealism,  to  understand  the  game  of  the 
universe,  as  a  thinking  animal,  as  a  result  of  which  our  finite 
blindness  and  liability  to  error  become  a  part  of  the  scheme 
of  the  universe.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  not  clear  why 
partial  knowledge  would  be  more  false  on  such  a  theory 
than  with  reference  to  any  ideal  of  complete  truth,  whether 
now  existing  or  to  be  progressively  realized.  The  ontolog- 
ical  existence  of  the  ideal  does  not  affect  the  problem  of 
consistency.  An  ideal  of  truth,  which  insists  upon  the  im- 
possibility of  truth,  is  the  most  irrational  theory  of  all. 
Truth  must  believe  in  itself,  in  its  possibility.  And  the 


ft. 


T}u  Content  of  Truth  117 

belief  in  complete  truth  implies  a  belief  in  the  teleological 
unity  of  the  universe,  in  some  manner,  and  so  postulates  in- 
ternal relations.  In  the  meantime  these  ideals  about  the 
universe  as  a  whole  are  over-beliefs,  however  important  may 
be  their  regulative  value.  Practically  we  have  truths  —  par- 
tial generalizations  about  our  world.  These  eventually  are 
taken  up  into  larger  systems,  coordinated  with  larger  masses 
of  facts.  And  through  these  readjustments,  the  significance 
of  the  contents  changes  even  though  the  part-contents,  of 
which  twe  have  previously  taken  account,  are  retained  as 
contents  in  this  larger  synthesis.  The  part-relations  of 
earth  and  sun  as  indicated  by  ordinary  perception  still  exist 
in  the  Copernican  theory,  but  their  significance — their  truth 
—  has  been  greatly  altered  in  the  larger  correlation  of  ex- 
perience. It  is  \\\Q  part-content — the  object  aimed  at  —  not 
the  part-significance,  which  remains  the  same  throughout 
the  truth-process.  Suppose  a  dog  to  undergo  a  surgical 
operation,  such  as  having  a  tooth  filled.  To  the  dog  the 
pain  suggests  nothing  but  violence  and  defence.  To  the 
dentist  it  suggests  professional  profit.  To  the  owner,  it 
means  a  happier  and  longer  future  for  a  pet  dog.  The  dog's 
and  the  master's  consciousness  each  have  to  do  with  the 
same  presented  content,  but  the  significance  is  different. 
The  dog's  significance  is  false,  while  the  master's  is  true. 
The  situation  here  has  only  one  true  context,  so  far  as  that 
specific  significance  is  concerned,  And  this  may  be  true 
of  every  content.  Theoretically,  at  any  rate,  the  idealistic 
world  presents  no  contradictions.  The  difficulties  on  which 
it  founders,  if  it  does  founder,  are  difficulties  of  fact,  not  of 
a  priori  consistency. 

While  I  cannot  hold  that  there  is  anything  contradictory 
in  internal  relations  or  in  the  conception  of  a  significant 


n8  Truth  and  Reality 

whole,  I  do  not  think  it  is  proven  that  reality  all  together 
is  such  a  whole.  So  far  as  we,  finites,  are  concerned,  it 
seems  clear  that  some  relations  are  of  an  external  type,  that 
is,  that  they  are  not  grounded  in  the  natures  of  their  terms  ; 
but  that  they  can  be  taken  in  other  relations  without  preju- 
dice to  their  character.  Our  abstract  symbols  can  be  taken 
over  and  over  again,  and  so  can  any  abstract  relations,  or 
qualities.  Our  serial  time  and  space  relations,  our  quanti- 
tative comparisons,  our  categories  of  likeness  and  differ- 
ence do  not,  as  subjective  ways  of  taking  our  facts,  in 
anywise  alter  the  facts  concerned.  That  you  follow  another 
man  by  the  clock,  that  you  happen  to  stand  next  him  in  the 
street,  that  you  happen  to  have  a  similar  nose,  that  you 
happen  to  be  a  head  taller  —  all  this  so  far  as  we  can  see 
may  be  quite  accidental  to  your  own  character.  Any  crea- 
ture of  logical  definition  can  be  taken  over  again  in  differ- 
ent contexts.  One  equation  can  be  substituted  for  another : 
2  +  2  =  3  +  1  so  far  as  the  abstract  requirements  of  quan- 
tity are  concerned. 

It  is  quite  another  matter,  however,  to  say  that  all  re- 
lations are  external,  that  they  are  never  grounded  in  their 
terms.  Such  a  statement,  in  our  finite  experience,  is  at 
least  as  halting  as  the  assumption  that  all  relations  are  in- 
ternal. Here  we  must,  owing  to  our  limitations,  proceed 
pragmatically,  and  take  experience  at  its  face  value.  And 
while  part  of  our  experience  seems  to  hang  together,  in 
this  external  and  additive  way,  other  parts  again  exhibit 
unmistakable  evidence  of  the  intimacy  of  purposive  over- 
lapping and  interpenetration.  Nor  is  this  true  merely  of 
significant  relations.  Causal  relations,  too,  imply  certain 
natures  on  the  part  of  the  terms  involved.  Causality  can- 
not be  regarded  as  a  mere  accidental  and  external  conjunc- 


The  Content  of  Truth  119 

tion  of  indifferent  facts,  as  Hume  would  have  us  believe.  It 
depends  not  merely  upon  sequence,  if  such  can  be  discerned, 
but  primarily  upon  the  nature  of  the  processes  involved. 
So  much  is  this  the  case  that  Leibniz  defined  causality  en- 
tirely in  terms  of  the  natures  of  the  monads,  and  denied  the 
efficacy  of  external  relations. 

Nor  can  we  get  around  the  problem  of  internal  and  ex- 
ternal relations  by  insisting  upon  the  diaphanous  character 
of  consciousness,  for  internal  relations  are  as  much  content 
relations  as  are  external,  and  so  are  not  constituted  by  the 
individual's  awareness  of  them.  To  be  sure,  internal  re- 
lations, such  as  truth,  imply  mind  for  their  existence,  or  at 
least  the  possibility  of  mind,  for  if  the  whole  world  should 
be  asleep,  this  would  destroy  the  reality  of  internal  rela- 
tions, unless  there  were  an  awakening  to  consciousness 
again.  We  do  not,  however,  create  the  relations  of  geom- 
etry any  more  than  the  relations  of  the  milky  way  by  our 
awareness  of  them. 

So  far  as  our  finite  experience  goes,  therefore,  we  must 
take  the  Universe  as  in  part  implying  internal  relations  or 
relations  of  teleological  significance ;  in  part  as  being  ca- 
pable of  being  taken  in  terms  of  external  relations,  or  at  any 
rate  external  to  our  finite  and  fragmentary  purposes.  So 
far  as  our  cognitive  interest  is  concerned,  at  least,  the 
larger  part  of  our  universe  seems  to  be  unaffected,  as  regards 
its  character,  by  our  taking  it.  This  is  not  true,  however, 
even  here,  where  our  attitude  influences  the  reality  of  the 
facts,  as  in  those  conditions  which  depend  upon  our 
volitional  set.  The  advantage  of  pragmatism  is  that,  in 
the  largeness  of  our  ignorance,  we  can  take  the  universe 
as  we  find  it  and  proceed  from  part  to  part  by  such  frag- 
mentary leadings  as  our  finite  thought  is  capable  of.  And 


I2O  Truth  and  Reality 

in  our  present  incomplete  state  of  knowledge,  at  any  rate, 
the  pluralistic  way  of  taking  reality  has  decided  advantages. 
Objects,  except  in  those  limited  cases  which  are  altered  by 
our  will,  seem  indifferent  or  neutral  so  far  as  our  cognitive 
attitude  is  concerned,  whatever  internal  relations  they  may 
imply  as  regards  their  own  content. 

The  controversy  as  regards  relations  involves  fundamen- 
tally the  whole  conception  of  the  relation  of  truth  to  reality, 
and  with  this  we  must  deal  more  fully  elsewhere.  We 
must  point  out,  however,  here  that  truth  is  not  foreign 
to  reality,  not  an  accidental  addition  to  reality,  not  a  mere 
tool  of  the  will.  Intelligence,  we  have  seen,  is  not  opposed 
to  instinct  or  intuition :  it  is  our  instinctive,  intuitive  life 
made  definite.  Instinct  is  vague  and  inchoate,  and  requires 
memory  and  reason  in  order  to  do  its  work,  to  complete 
its  insight,  to  reveal  to  itself  what  it  means.  Intelligence 
adds  definiteness  to  instinct.  Symbols,  whether  language 
or  concrete  imagery,  are  merely  instruments  in  the  service 
of  thought,  to  attain  to  this  definiteness  of  meaning  and 
conduct.  While  instinct  strives  to  realize  itself  at  random, 
intelligence  means  realization  in  accordance  with  the  spe- 
cific character  of  the  environment  —  the  molding  of  our 
theory  upon  the  anatomy  of  reality.  Intelligence  is  rooted 
in  the  demands  of  instinct,  and  instinct  becomes  organized 
and  significant  in  intelligence.  It  becomes  realized.  For 
truth  is  always  of  the  real,  bone  of  its  bone,  flesh  of  its 
flesh.  It  aims  at  specific  reality,  at  individual  fulfillment. 
It  is  positive,  and  not  merely  negative.  It  is  identification 
and  organization  and  not  mere  absence  of  doubt.  In  this 
identifying  and  conceptualizing,  we  must  indeed  select  and 
omit,  but  what  we  select  is  content  of  reality. 

The  eternal  and  abstract  essences,  which  have  occupied 


The  Content  of  Truth  121 

so  prominent  a  place  in  the  history  of  thought,  have  no 
existence  in  our  world  except  as  creatures  of  thought.  We 
can  abstract  our  geometric  relations,  our  qualitative  charac- 
ters, our  symbolic  entities,  and  deal  with  them  as  such. 
Thus  abstracted  from  the  matrix  of  experience,  they  be- 
come indeed  eternal  and  changeless,  but  they  exist  only 
within  our  abstract  purposes.  Materialistic  and  spirtualistic 
atoms  alike  are  the  result  of  this  activity  of  abstraction. 
And  since  the  facts  of  reality  are  themselves,  as  we  find 
them,  parts  of  the  concrete  world  of  interpenetrating  and 
flowing  processes,  our  atomic  entities  must  be  decomposed 
into  prime  atoms  or  qualities,  or  whatever  aspect  may 
interest  the  spectator  in  his  attempt  to  describe  and  predict 
reality.  But  their  indifference  and  independence  exist 
only  for  the  abstract  purposes  of  the  will,  and  in  the  service 
of  its  demands. 

Does  truth  preexist  ?  Does  thought  find  truth  or  create 
truth  ?  To  us  it  seems  that  thought  creates  truth,  in  the 
sense  of  a  significant  system,  rather  than  finds  it.  Truth 
seems  to  be  the  outcome  of  thought's  activity  in  tracing 
relations,  in  identifying  constancies  amidst  the  flux.  But 
even  from  our  finite  point  of  view  we  must  grant  at  least  a 
preexistent  fitness  for  truth.  Our  world  of  objects  and 
our  categories  of  intelligence  have  evolved  together;  or 
rather  the  latter  have  evolved  in  the  service  of  the  former. 
The  real  world,  therefore,  cannot  be  wholly  indifferent  to 
our  intellectual  demands.  There  are  not  two  sets  of  re- 
lations, existing  in  different  worlds  :  the  arbitrary  relations 
forced  upon  the  world  by  thought  on  the  one  hand  and  the 
unknowable  relations  existing  in  things  on  the  other.  But 
thought  is  at  home  in  the  world ;  is  the  outcome  of  its 
process;  the  revelation  in  part  at  least  of  its  inner  story. 


122  Truth  and  Reality 

Whether  the  story  of  the  universe  as  a  whole  is  itself  a 
story  of  experience  must  be  determined  through  the  success 
of  realizing  our  metaphysical  and  religious  demands  on 
that  basis.  We  at  any  rate  come  about  our  universals  post 
rent  as  extracted  from  the  real  world,  whether  they  exist 
ante  rem  or  not. 


CHAPTER  VII 

THE  POSTULATES  OF  TRUTH 

THE  pragmatic  movement  has  emphasized  practically 
altogether  \\\Q  function  of  truth  in  relation  to  life  as  a  whole. 
The  function  of  truth  is  to  regulate  conduct ;  and  truth, 
therefore,  is  valid  when  it  flows  into  its  anticipated  con- 
sequences. These  consequences  are  further  experiences. 
Epistemologically  truth  rests  on  experience ;  and  expe- 
rience, as  one  moment  of  individual  consciousness,  rests  on 
more  experience,  the  present  moment  becoming  confluent 
with  the  new  moments  in  the  ever  expanding  restless 
stream.  The  flow  of  this  stream  has  its  direction  deter- 
mined by  the  past  and  present  tendencies,  but  it  also  has  its 
own  individuality,  as  the  old  elements  flow  into  the  new 
situations,  whether  chemical  or  psychological. 

What  should  be  made  clear,  however,  is  that  pragmatism 
is  a  theory  of  the  function  of  truth,  and  does  not  deal  with 
the  whole  problem.  By  emphasizing  this  we  may  be  able 
to  attract  attention  to  the  far  larger  and  more  complicated 
problem  of  the  form  of  truth.  To  be  sure,  even  in  dealing 
with  the  problem  of  function,  pragmatism  has  been  inclined 
to  limit  itself  to  the  biological  function  of  truth  —  truth  as 
a  factor  in  the  adjustment  to  the  perceptual  environment, 
or  a  tool  for  dealing  with  perceptual  situations.  Pragma- 
tism has  been  inclined  to  neglect  the  sporting  interest  in 
truth  —  truth  as  setting  its  own  problems,  choosing  its  own 
constitution,  and  thus  elaborating  its  logical  consequences 

123 


124  Truth  and  Reality 

to  harmonize  with  its  posited  world.  But  this,  while  it 
alters  our  conception  of  the  scope  of  truth,  does  not  funda- 
mentally alter  our  conception  of  its  function,  which  still 
remains  to  regulate  conduct  —  the  conduct  of  the  under- 
standing as  well  as  the  adaptation  to  a  perceptual  environ- 
ment. 

But  granting  that  thought  comes  to  light  in  the  stress 
and  strain  of  experience  —  whether  forced  upon  us  by  the 
environment  or  posited  as  the  logical  play-ground  of  the 
will  —  there  remains  the  problem  of  the  nature  of  thought 
itself.  Is  the  form  of  thought  originated  by  the  practical 
situation  —  the  consciousness  of  difficulty  or  disorganiza- 
tion out  of  which  it  arises?  In  the  case  of  generating 
electricity  by  friction,  say  by  two  sticks  of  wood,  we  are 
setting  free  a  preexistent  energy,  the  nature  of  which  we 
must  respect;  and  the  friction  simply  furnishes  a  condition 
for  its  manifestation.  Is  it  so  with  thought  ?  Or  is  thought 
created  outright  by  doubt  ?  Does  it  really  grow  out  of  the 
infra-logical  antecedents  ?  In  that  case,  is  the  form,  too  — 
the  laws  of  thought  —  created  ?  Are  they  set  by  the  will  as 
its  temporal  conventions,  or  must  they  be  acknowledged  by 
the  will  as  eternal  ?  In  the  former  case,  are  they  just  what 
the  individual  posits  them  as  being,  or  are  they  universal  ? 
But,  if  without  conventional  agreement  we  find  ourselves 
acknowledging  these  laws  whenever  we  think,  they  would 
seem  to  be  independent  of  the  will  and  have  a  preexistent 
character.  In  Plato's  terminology,  they  would  seem  to  be 
"  recollected ' '  rather  than  created  in  our  coming  to  conscious- 
ness of  them.  The  laws  of  thought  would  seem  to  be 
discovered  through  their  use  in  experience,  rather  than 
made. 

If  we  look  forward  to  the  end  of  thought,  instead  of 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  125 

backward  to  its  origin,  is  thought  simply  a  tool  to  an  alogical 
end  ?  Or  does  thought  enter  into  the  end  of  life  as  an 
intrinsic  factor  —  not  as  a  scaffolding  merely  for  a  higher 
stage  of  mystic  immediacy  or  biological  activity,  but  as  the 
law  of  the  process  of  life  ?  What  relation  does  thought, 
with  its  postulate,  bear  to  life  as  a  whole?  Such,  and 
many  other  questions,  still  remain,  after  we  have  agreed 
upon  the  regulative  function  of  thought  in  experience.  To 
ignore  the  structural  aspect  of  thought  means  a  very  in- 
vertebrate theory  of  knowledge. 

One  thing  is  certain,  that  the  teleological  value  of  thought 
cannot  be  understood  apart  from  its  correctness,  its  tech- 
nique. The  syllogism,  with  its  rules,  is  a  valuable  machine 
for  abstracting  and  investigating  valid  thought  relations,  in 
spite  of  the  contumely  heaped  upon  it  What  is  true  of 
the  syllogism,  as  a  device  for  ascertaining  formal  relations, 
is  true  likewise  of  the  so-called  inductive  canons  for  as- 
certaining causal  relations  amongst  facts.  The  practicality 
of  our  thinking  about  perceptual  situations  lies  in  its  being 
correct  thinking,  and  Mill's  canons  are  an  important  device 
for  such  procedure.  If  it  is  true  that  the  procedure  explains 
the  value  of  the  device,  it  is  also  true  that  the  procedure  is 
made  possible  by  its  being  a  correct  device. 

Are  these  rules  arbitrary  ?  The  rules  of  athletics  are  not 
arbitrary,  though  they  may  seem  so  to  the  spectator.  They 
are  the  result  of  studying  the  laws  governing  both  the  con- 
stitution of  the  players  and  the  appreciation  of  the  spec- 
tators, so  as  to  produce,  on  the  whole,  the  best  result  for 
player  and  spectator  alike.  The  conditions  governing  the 
game  may  be  said  to  preexist  in  human  nature  and  to  be  bind- 
ing if  you  choose  to  play  the  game  and  to  play  it  effectively. 
So  with  the  laws  of  thought.  The  question,  then,  arises : 


126  Truth  and  Reality 

What  are  those  laws  of  thought  which  in  all  our  reflective 
procedure  we  must  respect  ?  And  what  is  the  basis  of  their 
authority  ?  To  begin  with  the  first  question :  What  postu- 
lates are  implied  in  all  thinking  and  condition  its  procedure  ? 
I  shall  try  to  show  that  there  are  four  presuppositions  or 
laws  which  are  implied  in  all  our  knowing,  viz. :  the  law  of 
consistency;  the  law  of  totality;  the  subject-object  form,  or 
the  law  that  knowledge  must  be  representative ;  and  the 
law  of  finitude.  The  use  of  these  terms  will  become  clear, 
I  trust,  in  the  discussion. 

i.    The  Law  of  Consistency 

First  of  all  it  will  be  generally  agreed  that  we  presuppose 
consistency.  Under  the  law  of  consistency  I  include  what 
are  usually  termed  two  laws  —  the  law  of  identity  and  the 
law  of  contradiction.  It  requires  no  proof  to  show  that 
these  are  merely  different  emphases  of  the  same  meaning. 
If  we  use  the  old  formula,  A  is  A,  to  symbolize  the  so-called 
law  of  identity,  the  law  of  contradiction  simply  brings  out 
the  implication  that  if  A  must  be  taken  as  A,  if  black  must 
be  taken  as  black  and  Socrates  as  Socrates,  throughout  the 
logical  procedure,  A  cannot  also  be  taken  in  the  same  sense 
as  not- A.  This  is  true,  but  it  is  an  implication  rather  than 
an  independent  law.  Fortunately,  the  concept  of  consist- 
ency comprises  both  of  these  implications,  viz. :  that  for 
purposes  of  thought  we  must  be  able  to  take  A  as  A,  and 
that  if  we  must  thus  take  it,  we  cannot  take  it  as  not- A 

But  the  term  consistency  has  a  further  advantage.  It 
not  only  comprehends  both  of  the  old  formulas,  but  it  also 
brings  out  what  they  failed  to  do,  namely,  that  it  is  identity 
within  a  variety  of  individuals  and  changes  with  which  we 
are  concerned.  Truth  would  be  meaningless  within  an 

* 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  127 

abstract  world  in  which  A  is  bare  A.  It  is  the  constancy 
of  A,  as  making  possible  description  and  prediction,  that 
makes  truth  mean  something.  The  law  of  consistency 
means  that  in  the  variety  of  experienced  facts  and  changes, 
there  must  be  a  certain  constancy  of  content,  if  we  are  to 
make  any  predicates  about  our  world.  Unless  we  can  take 
our  abstract  meanings,  qualities,  relations,  or  whatever  we 
may  be  actively  interested  in,  as  the  same,  in  spite  of  flux, 
we  can  make  no  judgments  or  inferences.  This  means, 
formally  expressed,  that  we  must  take  A  as  A  throughout 
our  logical  procedure,  and  that  we  cannot  take  A  as  not-^4, 
if  we  would  reason  about  the  meanings  or  things  of  our 
experience.  This  implies  that,  for  logical  purposes  at  least, 
there  are  such  recognizable  identities  as  furnish  leadings  or 
threads  to  the  plurality  and  flux  of  experience. 

Identity  in  the  variety  of  situations,  empirical  or  formal, 
must  always  be  taken  as  identity  for  a  purpose,  in  order  to 
be  concerned  with  truth.  Mere  repetition  per  se  would 
have  no  significance  for  truth.  Animals,  too,  have  to 
adjust  themselves  to  a  world  of  uniformities;  and  they 
develop  instincts  and  habits,  but  no  truth.  It  must  be 
identity  as  leading  to  identification  ;  and  this  means  that 
the  situations  may,  in  other  respects,  be  quite  diverse.  In 
fact,  here  lies  the  significance  of  the  identification  —  in  tak- 
ing the  somehow  different  as  identical  for  the  purpose. 
4  =  2  +  2  for  the  purpose.  The  Jones  of  to-day,  however 
outwardly  changed  from  the  Jones  of  your  school-days,  is 
still  the  same  in  fundamental  characteristics,  and  merits 
the  same  loyalty  and  friendship. 

We  can  see  that  nominalism,  in  the  bald  sense  of  absolute 
disparateness,  would  make  truth  impossible.  In  such  a 
world  there  could  be  no  concepts  and  no  inference,  as  each 


1"^ 


^-^tV>v.  Q 

.  4  YWr  T 


128  Truth  and  Reality 

particular  content  must  be  taken  as  unique.  Nor  is  it 
necessary  to  go  to  the  opposite  extreme,  and  speak  of 
universals  or  identities  as  existing  prior  to  the  instances, 
and  these  as  differentiations  of  this  identity,  as  even  Bosan- 
quet  does.  This  makes  knowledge  quite  as  impossible  as 
does  pure  nominalism,  for  it  is,  absurd  to  suppose  that  from 
identity  any  instances  could  be  differentiated.  It  is  enough 
for  truth  that  certain  characteristics  can  be  taken  as  the 
same  in  various  individuals  or  groups,  and  that  this  makes  it 
possible  to  say  something  about  the  conduct  of  these  individ- 
uals or  groups  so  far  as  these  characteristics  are  concerned. 

Nor  is  a  purely  dynamic  nominalism  any  more  possible. 
To  be  sure,  truth  deals  with  a  world  of  change.  But 
change  need  not  be  chance  or  absolute  discontinuity  of 
process.  In  so  far  as  such  is  the  case,  truth  of  course  is 
impossible.  Change  may  be  circular,  or  practically  so; 
and  it  is  a  world  with  a  certain  uniformity  of  characteristics, 
however  much  it  may  change,  with  which  truth  must  deal. 
It  is  only  in  so  far  as  our  world  of  experience  can  be  taken 
as  constant,  that  we  can  have  science,  though  of  course  such 
a  statement  would  be  meaningless  if  we  did  not  deal  with  a 
world  of  change. 

The  law  of  consistency  always  has  to  do  with  meanings. 
The  meanings  may  be  abstract  or  hypothetical  merely, 
and  our  interest  may  be  in  their  formal  relations.  Or  the 
meanings  may  refer  to  qualities  and  relations  in  concrete 
experience,  and  so  may  be  concerned  with  existence.  But 
in  any  case  the  law  of  consistency  refers  to  the  identity  of 
meaning,  and  holds  that,  from  an  identical  content,  identical 
consequences  must  follow ;  so  that  if  certain  consequences 
follow  from  M  in  the  case  of  P,  the  same  consequences 
must  follow  from  M  in  the  case  of  5. 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  129 

The  law  of  consistency  applied  to  the  concrete  mean- 
ings of  experience  —  qualities,  relations,  or  whatever  they 
may  be  —  means  that  you  cannot  take  the  same  fact  as 
A  and  not-A  A  thing  cannot  be  taken  as  having  the 
quality  of  A  and  the  quality  of  not- A,  white  and  not-white, 
in  the  same  respect.  It  does  not  deal  with  the  question 
whether  a  thing  can  have  the  quality  A  and  not-^4  in  the 
same  respect.  The  law  of  identity  is  forced  upon  us  irre- 
spective of  the  object,  though  inasmuch  as  reality  is  for  us 
what  it  must  be  taken  as,  in  the  procedure  of  experience, 
we  naturally  extend  the  law  of  our  thinking  to  things  as 
well.  In  this  there  can  be  no  harm,  if  we  know  what  we 
are  doing  and  are  not  postulating  some  occult  harmony  to 
cover  up  our  previous  dualism  of  thought  and  things,  cre- 
ated by  our  own  assumptions.  One  thing  is  certain,  the 
world  of  experienced  things  is  to  some  extent  describable, 
and  so  must  have  some  degree  of  identity. 

That  A  is  not  not-A,  that  sour  is  not  sweet  or  any  other 
quality  within  the  universe  of  taste,  involves  no  contradic- 
tion. They  can  still  hang  together  within  one  system.  In 
fact  there  can  be  no  system,  if  there  is  not  difference.  Being 
and  not-being,  as  pure  abstractions,  do  not  imply  each  other. 
They  are  exclusive.  But  as  pure  abstractions  they  are 
also  indistinguishable.  They  can  have  meaning  only 
within  a  context.  And  when  we  really  develop  their 
meaning,  instead  of  bandying  terms,  we  find  that  they 
hang  together  by  their  edges  —  that  we  cannot  define  one 
without  implying  the  other  within  a  system  of  meaning 
which  posits  them  as  aspects  of  itself.  Bradley  would 
argue  that,  since  A  cannot  possibly  be  not-A,  therefore 
they  cannot  be  related  in  any  manner.  For  suppose  they 
were  like  in  any  way.  Then  in  so  far  they  must  be 


130  Truth  and  Reality 

identical  or  partake  of  a  common  term.  This  leads  to  an 
infinite  regress.  But  what  is  this  but  playing  with  terms  ? 
Of  course,  if  A  and  not-A  be  made  exclusive  by  definition, 
they  cannot  belong  together.  But  that  does  not  prevent  our 
actual  A  and  B,  as  experienced,  from  belonging  together 
within  a  system,  though  perhaps  not  always  one  of  logical 
implication,  as  Hegel  thought.  Experience  is  not  chopped 
up  with  a  hatchet,  not  made  up  of  isolated  abstractions.  As 
immediate,  the  qualities  of  experience  are  unique.  But  as 
immediate  they  are  neither  here  nor  there,  neither  this  nor 
that,  neither  more  nor  less  —  not  truth.  It  is  because  these 
facts  are  capable  of  being  sorted  into  series  and  classes, 
on  the  basis  of  degree  or  kind,  that  we  have  science.  And 
this  distinguishing  of  degrees  or  kinds,  identities  or  differ- 
ences in  the  world  of  individual  facts,  does  not  seem  to 
disrupt.  It  contradicts  neither  their  existential  nor  their 
appreciative  unity. 

Two  aspects  are  involved  in  the  concept  of  consistency, 
as  I  am  using  it:  First,  that  terms  must  have  an  identical 
meaning,  must  be  taken  as  the  same  throughout  the  argu- 
ment. Otherwise  we  shall  not  be  talking  about  the  same 
thing,  and  so  shall  be  guilty  of  the  fallacy  of  four  terms. 
This  use  of  the  term  consistency  is  closely  bound  up  with 
the  other  aspect :  namely,  that  from  identical  characteristics 
follow  identical  consequences,  whether  we  deal  with  rela- 
tions or  qualities,  or  whatever  the  selected  content  may  be, 
and  whether  the  individual  wujtsBe  the  same,  or  we  be 
dealing  with  new  groups  of  facts.  A  case  of  this  would 
be  Euclid's  postulate:  "Things  equal  to  the  same  thing 
are  equal  to  each  other."  Stated  in  a  more  generic  form: 
If  any  individuals  or  groups  of  individuals  are  identical  in 
some  respect,  they  can  be  exchanged  so  far  as  that  charac- 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  131 

teristic  is  concerned.  This  is  equally  involved  in  deductive 
and  inductive  inferences.  What  we  must  be  careful  about 
in  each  case  is  to  isolate  or  distribute  the  identity,  to  see 
not  merely  that  there  is  identity  in  the  situations  dealt 
with,  but  that  it  is  significant  or  relevant  identity  —  identity 
in  the  same  respect,  i.e.,  that  it  pertains  to  the  conse- 
quences which  we  try  to  deduce.  This  is  reduced  to  a  tech- 
nique in  the  syllogism  by  rules  such  as,  the  middle  term 
must  be  distributed  at  least  once,  no  term  must  be  distributed 
in  the  conclusion  which  is  not  distributed  in  the  premises, 
there  must  not  be  more  than  three  terms,  and  both  premises 
cannot  be  particular  or  negative.  As  regards  causal  re- 
lations the  technique  of  discovering  this  identity  has  been 
systematized  in  Mill's  canons,  the  ideal  of  which  is  the 
method  of  difference,  which  means  precisely  a  distributed 
identity.  We  thus  proceed  to  sort  our  facts  into  classes 
and  series  with  determinate  characteristics  and  predicta- 
bility. The  success  may  be  varied,  and  even  with  cumula- 
tive cooperation  and  specialization,  must  necessarily  be  slow, 
considering  the  complexity  of  our  world.  Sometimes  the 
result  of  scientific  investigation  is  simplification  of  hy- 
pothesis, as  in  reducing  magnetism  and  light  to  electricity. 
Again,  new  and  unforeseen  data  come  to  our  ken,  necessi- 
tating fresh  assorting,  as  in  the  recent  discovery  of  the  radio- 
active elements.  But  the  progress  of  science,  physical  and 
psychological,  is  evidence  to  how  great  an  extent  the  world 
of  our  experience  lends  itself  to  conceptual  manipulation. 
A  great  deal  has  been  said  justly  against  substituting 
mere  analogy  for  proof,  as  the  human  mind  in  its  laziness 
so  often  does.  This  must  not  blind  us  to  the  fact,  how- 
ever, that  we  must  proceed  by  analogy  —  the  seeming 
identity  in  the  new  set  of  facts  with  situations  that  we 


132  Truth  and  Reality 

have  tabulated  and  learned  to  meet  in  past  experience. 
Newton's  theory  of  gravitation,  Darwin's  theory  of  the 
origin  of  species,  are  splendid  instances  of  framing  hypothe- 
ses on  the  basis  of  analogy  and  with  successful  outcome. 
We  must  be  careful,  however,  to  make  certain,  by  obser- 
vation and  experiment,  that  the  likeness  is  relevant  like- 
ness—  that  the  consequences  which  we  try  to  predict 
follow  from  the  identical  characters  which  we  have  se- 
lected. Two  men  may  be  identical  in  being  tall  or  black 
or  Italian,  but  it  does  not  follow  that  you  can  predict  from 
one  to  the  other  as  regards  reliability,  though  that  is  the 
way  we  often  implicitly  proceed. 

As  the  law  of  consistency  means  that  an  object  of  expe- 
rience must  be  taken  as  the  same  (quality  or  relation)  in 
the  same  respect ;  or,  expressing  it  negatively,  that  an  ob- 
ject cannot  have  different  predicates  in  the  same  respect, 
-"this  will  be  seen  to  include  what  Lotze  has  called  "  the 
disjunctive  law  of  thought,"  a  species  of  which,  in  the  case 
of  only  two  alternatives,  would  be  the  so-called  law  of  ex- 
cluded middle.  To  use  a  concrete  instance :  A  rose  a  priori 
may  be  qualified  by  any  one  of  a  number  of  colors,  but  as 
a  matter  of  fact  it  can  be  taken  only  as  having  one  color 
in  the  same  respect.  And  if  it  possesses  one,  for  example, 
red,  it  cannot  possess  any  of  the  other  colors  at  that  point. 
Whether  you  artificially  dichotomize  your  universe  of  color 
as  red  and  not-red  for  the  purpose,  or  state  the  actual  dis- 
junction of  alternatives  possible,  the  result  is  the  same. 
An  object  cannot  both  be  taken  as  having  a  quality  and 
as  having  a  different  quality  in  the  same  respect.  The 
"  disjunctive  law  "  is  hardly  even  a  corollary.  It  is  rather 
the  explicit  statement  of  the  law  of  consistency,  as  pre- 
viously used. 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  133 

If  the  traditional  laws  must  be  regarded  as  different  em- 
phases at  most  of  the  same  principle,  they  have  their  mean- 
ing, nevertheless,  as  psychological  stages  in  making  explicit 
the  law  of  consistency.  From  this  point  of  view  the  con- 
sciousness that  A  must  be  taken  as  A,  in  a  universe  of  dis- 
course, is  less  distinct  than  the  consciousness  that  A 
cannot  be  taken  as  not-A.  But  the  full  significance  of 
the  law  of  consistency  is  expressed  in  the  "disjunctive 
law,"  viz.,  that  our  universe  of  discourse  must  be  capable 
of  suqh  disjunction  that  A  can  be  distinguished  from  B 
and  every  other  possible  predicate  in  the  same  respect  — 
only  one  of  which  can  be  taken  as  qualifying  the  subject 
and  thus  be  predicated  in  distinction  from  the  rest. 

As  corollaries  or  implications  of  the  law  of  consistency, 
we  would  have  the  axiom  that  what  can  be  predicated, 
whether  affirmed  or  denied,  of  a  kind  can  also  be  predi- 
cated of  that  kind's  kind,  which  is  so  vital  in  all  our  de- 
ductive procedure.  And  also  that  what  is  true  of  one 
group  of  facts  is  true  of  another  group,  if  the  practical 
consequences  follow  from  characteristics  which  the  groups 
have  in  common.  And  thus  we  can  extend  our  knowledge 
by  analogy  to  new  cases  and  test  its  application  there. 

2.    The  Law  of  Totality 

But  though  we  are  able  thus  to  establish  kinds  or  sys- 
tems of  fact,  with  their  definite  connections  and  predicta- 
bility in  suo  genere,  the  question  still  remains  whether  these 
systems  cohere  into  a  whole,  hang  together  as  kinds,  or 
whether  perhaps  our  world  is  made  up  of  disparate  or  par- 
allel systems,  whether  two  or  infinite  in  number.  Now  to 
be  knowable  it  will  be  seen  that  somehow  the  various 
systems  must  hang  together  at  least  with  our  cognitive 


134  Truth  and  Reality 

purposes.  We  must  have  systematic  connection  in  the  large 
{in  dem  Grossen),  as  well  as  unique  determination  within 
the  one  kind  of  series  (in  dem  Kleinen).  Taking  num- 
ber as  one  illustration,  not  only  must  the  various  series, 
finite  and  transfinite,  be  self-consistent,  but  we  also  demand 
that  they  shall  form  a  complete  whole.  Now  this  postu- 
late of  systematic  connection  in  the  large,  I  would  call  the 
law  of  totality. 

This  is  broader  than  Leibniz's  law  of  sufficient  reason  : 
Nothing  happens  without  a  reason  why  it  should  be  so 
rather  than  otherwise.  The  law  of  totality  does  not  em- 
phasize teleological  connection  as  over  against  causal,  as  has 
generally  been  the  use  of  the  law  of  sufficient  reason.  It 
merely  emphasizes  that  facts  do  not  exist  as  isolated  indi- 
viduals or  isolated  groups  in  our  experience,  but  belong 
with  other  facts ;  that  reality,  as  we  know  it,  hangs  to- 
gether by  its  edges,  so  that  we  can  pass  from  one  fact  to 
another,  either  directly  or  by  intermediaries ;  and  that  only 
so  can  we  know  it.  It  does  not  mean  that  every  fact  makes 
a  difference  to  every  other ;  that  our  fancies  alter  our  gravi- 
tational relations  to  the  Milky  Way.  This  would  be  im- 
possible to  show.  On  the  contrary,  we  know  that  some 
facts  seem  to  make  no  direct  difference  to  a  given  group 
of  other  facts ;  and  some  make  a  certain  kind  of  difference 
only  under  certain  conditions  of  intensity  or  complexity. 
It  makes  no  difference  to  a  color  in  what  part  of  a  space 
or  time  series  it  is  located,  whether  perceived  yesterday  or 
to-day,  here  or  in  China,  given  the  same  concrete  setting. 
But  the  number  of  vibrations  per  second  do  make  a  dif- 
ference. Even  here,  however,  on  account  of  the  struc- 
tural conditions,  a  certain  intensity  of  vibration  is  required 
to  perceive  light  at  all,  and  a  certain  number  of  vibrations 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  135 

per  second  must  be  added  to  perceive  another  kind  of  light. 
Experience,  as  we  can  take  account  of  it,  does  not  proceed 
by  infinitesimal  transitions,  but  by  finite  drops  or  bucket . 
fulls.  The  law  means  that  facts  possess  such  uniformities 
or  similarities  that  we  can  pass  from  one  to  another,  under 
determinate  conditions,  if  not  immediately,  through  a  series 
of  intermediaries.  If  my  thought  does  not  directly  affect 
other  bodies  in  space,  it  may  do  so  indirectly  through  the 
difference  it  makes  to  my  own  body.  But,  by  some  edges, 
some  common  attribute,  all  the  parts  of  our  world  hang 
together.  Mind  must  make  a  difference,  under  determinate 
conditions,  to  mind,  and  body  to  body,  and  mind  to  body 
and  body  to  mind,  in  so  far  as  they  are  parts  of  our  ex- 
perience and  known  by  our  experience. 

The  constitution  of  the  human  mind  makes  the  causal 
category  a  pervasive  one.  To  know  our  world  means  that 
its  various  objects  can  make  a  difference  either  directly  or 
indirectly  to  our  minds.  This,  in  the  case  of  the  physical 
world,  means  a  causal  difference.  To  speak  of  physical 
changes  as  parallel  to  thought  would  mean  that  the  mind 
can  take  account  of  objective  existences  that  make  no  differ- 
ence to  it,  which  is  absurd.  That  our  ideally  posited  world 
of  objects  makes  a  difference  to  our  purposes  requires  no 
elucidation.  Thus  widely  interpreted,  the  law  of  totality 
means  that  the  world  with  which  knowledge  is  concerned 
cannot  exist  in  compartments.  It  is  a  command  to  look 
for  connection.  In  a  certain  sense  it  may  be  taken  as 
equivalent  to  Spinoza's  conception  of  substance,  without 
assuming  a  priori  that  "the  order  and  connection  of  ideas 
is  the  same  as  the  order  and  connection  of  things."  We 
have  to  do  here  only  with  things  as  experienced.  We  might, 
however,  agree  to  Spinoza's  axiom  that  "things  which 


136  Truth  and  Reality 

have  nothing  in  common  cannot  be  understood,  the  one 
by  means  of  the  other ;  the  conception  of  one  does  not  in- 
volve the  conception  of  the  other  " —  meaning  by  "  in  com- 
mon "  merely  that  the  things  must  be  capable  of  making  a 
difference  to  each  other  under  certain  conditions,  and 
especially,  directly  or  indirectly,  to  our  cognitive  pur- 
poses. We  cannot  know  universes  split  off  from  our 
own,  if  such  were  existentially  possible. 

In  spite,  however,  of  Spinoza's  insistence  upon  the 
unity  of  the  one  substance,  he  left  us  two  disparate  parallel 
systems  which  can  make  no  difference  to  each  other,  have 
no  common  attribute  —  the  world  of  thought  and  the  world 
of  extension.  Our  concern  here  is  not  with  the  meta- 
physical possibility  of  such  a  conception.  But  for  episte- 
mological  purposes,  we  must  assume  not  merely  that  the 
universe  can  be  sorted  into  kinds,  but  that  these  kinds 
somehow  hang  together,  that  one  part  of  our  experience 
coheres  with  another  part,  either  directly  or  by  means  of 
intermediaries.  Only  in  such  a  world  would  social  objects 
be  possible.  Facts  thus  have  not  merely  a  unique  deter- 
mination within  their  own  special  system,  but  have  a  uni- 
versal reference,  cohering  as  a  whole.  And  this  is  what  I 
mean  by  the  law  of  totality. 

And  how  do  they  cohere  ?  I  can  conceive  of  only  two 
ways :  either  as  cause  and  effect,  or  as  means  within  a  pur- 
pose, logical,  ethical,  or  esthetic.  And  it  is  not  necessary 
for  epistemological  purposes,  whether  it  is  for  metaphys- 
ical or  not,  to  reduce  these  to  one.  It  is  not  enough  that 
facts  are  together  in  one  space  and  one  time.  They  might 
be  thus  together  and  yet  exist  in  compartments.  Space 
and  time  do  not  unify.  On  the  contrary  the  same  presup- 
position of  totality  applies  to  our  space  and  time  systems. 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  137 

We  assume  the  unity  of  space  on  the  basis  of  the  law  of 
totality,  i.e.,  because  we  believe  that  our  universe  of  facts, 
spread  out  in  space,  hangs  together.  And  so  with  the 
unity  of  our  social  time  construction  or  history.  Empiri- 
cally we  do  come  upon  functionally  dissociated  time  series 
in  experience,  as  in  automatic  writing  and  trance,  but  they 
are  cognitive  realities  only  when  connection  is  established 
for  some  subject.  Facts  must  run  into  each  other  some 
way,  causally  or  Ideologically,  to  make  the  unity  required 
for  cognitive  purposes.  And  as  all  teleological  unities  are 
also  psychological  events,  therefore  all  facts  must  in  the 
last  analysis  be  causally  conceived,  according  to  some 
definite  relationship,  as  objects  of  knowledge. 

Nor  does  the  law  of  totality  mean  merely  that  the  facts 
of  experience  are  a  collection  of  such  a  kind  that  we  can 
use  connective  symbols  as  and  or  with  or  on,  etc. ;  not 
merely  that  we  are  conscious  of  the  facts  together,  which 
we  are  only  to  a  small  extent,  but  that  facts  make  a  dif- 
ference to  some  other  facts,  become  confluent  with  some 
other  parts  of  experience,  in  a  systematic  way.  If  know- 
able,  they  are  not  merely  lumped  as  ands  and  withs,  but 
strung  with  identities  which  we  can  disentangle  either 
causally  or  ideologically.  This  we  postulate  at  the  very 
outset  of  logical  investigation.  Only  in  this  way  are  con- 
sequences predictable,  formally  or  materially.  Whether 
the  laws  of  thought  are  coercive  over  things  or  not,  they 
hold  for  our  experience  of  things,  actual  and  possible.  And 
that  is  all  that  is  logically  important.  The  form  of  experi- 
ence at  any  rate  is  predetermined. 

Because  we  must  assume  that  facts,  in  order  to  be  known, 
must  be  capable  of  making  a  difference  to  other  facts  and 
so,  either  mediately  or  immediately,  to  our  powers  of  know- 


138  Truth  and  Reality 

ing,  it  does  not  follow  that  we  must  assume  that  facts,  in 
advance  of  being  known,  must  be  strung  on  the  unity  of 
thought.  Facts  in  order  to  become  known  must  be  strung 
upon  our  hypotheses,  become  a  part  of  our  purposes,  but 
that  does  not  prove  that  they  can  only  exist  as  thus  strung. 
It  is  through  such  stringing  that  facts  come  to  have  their 
significance  for  our  human  experience,  but  that  does  not 
prove  that  they  then  begin  to  exist  or  that  thus  they  must 
exist  in  a  larger  mind.  Facts  satisfy  the  law  of  totality 
when  they  are  capable  of  making  some  difference  to  our 
purposes  under  definable  conditions.  This  is  quite  dif- 
ferent from  holding  that,  because^  we  can  string  things  on 
our  unity  of  apperception,  therefore  they  must  already  be 
part  of  a  transcendental  unity  of  thought. 

3.    The  Law  of  Duality,  or  the  Presupposition  of  the  Sub- 
ject-object Relation 

This  is  involved  in  all  thinking ;  and  the  attempt  to  state 
the  subject  as  object  or  vice  versa,  for  thought  purposes, 
gives  rise  to  a  paradoxical  infinite  which  is  not  a  progress 
toward  a  limit,  but  which  simply  means  that  you  cannot 
transcend  the  subject-object  relation  while  you  remain 
within  the  concept  of  thought.  This  paradoxical  answer 
resembles  the  one  you  get  in  number  when  you  ask  what 
number  is  less  than  the  least  conceivable  fraction.  To 
which  the  answer  is :  zero,  which  is  not  a  number  at  all, 
and  so  beyond  the  series  of  fractions.  The  difference  is 
that  the  conception  of  an  infinite  series  in  the  case  of 
number  has  a  warrant  in  the  progress  toward  a  limit,  which 
is  not  the  case  in  the  subject-object  relation.  Here  nothing 
is  gained  by  the  repetition,  once  you  have  grasped  the  law 

that  in  every  judgment,  including  the  reflection  upon  itself, 
^  vJU-Lflu^-X-  «••»  V>\wtXl     ^*-         *^M 

TV    U^  \ 

^ 

' 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  139 

the  subject-object  relation  is  involved.  You  do  not  get 
a  thought,  at  infinity,  which  is  neither  subject  nor  object. 

A  good  deal  has  been  said  about  the  self-representative 
character  of  thought  and  its  supposedly  implied  infinite. 
Now,  it  is  quite  true  that  the  proposition,  no  subject  with- 
out an  object,  as  a  law  of  thought,  must  be  self -applicable, 
i.e.,  the  judgment,  as  regards  the  subject-object  relation 
of  thought,  itself  involves  the  subject-object  relation.  Like 
all  true  presuppositions  of  thought,  the  subject-object  pre- 
suppqsition  is  circular.  Thought  activity  always  means 
the  discovery  of  the  relation  of  a  selected  content  to  a 
system ;  and  to  this  the  reflection  upon  the  subject-object 
character  is  no  exception.  We  simply  become  conscious 
of  the  fact  that  the  self -representative  judgment  is  an  in- 
stance of  the  universally  representative  character  of  thought 
and  differs  in  no  wise,  so  far  as  the  application  of  this  law 
is  concerned,  from  any  other  judgment. 

Now,  thanks  to  language,  this  representative  statement, 
whether  self-representative  or  other-representative,  can  be 
repeated  upon  itself  to  infinity.  And  this,  no  doubt,  has 
its  own  value  as  a  logical  sport,  whether  in  the  philosophy 
of  number  or  in  other  speculations ;  but  it  does  not  in  any- 
wise clarify  the  nature  of  thought.  For  purposes  of  episte- 
mology,  the  self -representative  character  of  thought  simply 
means  that  the  subject-object  relation  as  a  presupposition 
of  thought  is  self-applicable.  It  certainly  does  not  prove 
that  truth  is  an  infinite  series. 

Neither  does  the  universality  of  the  subject-object  relation 
in  all  our  thinking  prove  that  it  must  hold  universally  for 
existence  ;  that  because  we  cannot  think  an  object  without 
a  subject,  therefore  all  thinkable  reality  must  be  involved 
in  the  circle  of  this  subject-object  relation ;  ergo :  all  reality 


140  Truth  and  Reality 

must  be  a  spiritual  or  reflective  unity.  This  has  been  a 
favorite  argument  for  idealism  and  is  certainly  a  short 
cut.  But  is  it  valid  ?  We  must  remember  that  the  subject- 
object  presupposition  only  holds  for  our  thinking  of  reality. 
It  can  only  be  a  presupposition  therefore  for  reality  which 
thinks.  Our  reflecting  upon  the  stone  does  not  necessarily 
make  the  stone  reflective,  and  so  does  not  necessarily  sweep 
the  real  stone  within  the  subject-object  circle  of  our  thought, 
in  the  sense  of  its  existence  being  conditioned  by  its  being 
known.  What  parts  of  reality  think  and  what  do  not  think 
must  be  decided  upon  evidence,  and  not  by  any  a  priori 
epistemological  presuppositions.  All  we  can  show  is  that 
these  must  hold  for  thinking  beings,  that  they  are  presup- 
posed in  our  thinking,  and  that  our  denial  of  them  affirms 
them.  But  we  cannot  show  a  priori  what  beings  are  think- 
ing beings  or  that  the  universe  as  a  whole  is  a  thinking 
animal. 

The  relation  of  the  referent  to  the  referatum,  of  subject 
and  object,  in  the  judgment  relation  of  the  living  thought 
process  is  different  from  the  reference  within  a  logical 
context,  taken  as  abstracted  from  the  real  subject.  This 
has  often  been  lost  sight  of  in  the  definition  of  the  judg- 
ment. The  meaning  of  the  proposition,  however  complex 
its  internal  organization  may  be,  only  figures  as  a  judgment, 
when  it  is  taken  up  into  the  active  thought  context  at  the 
time.  This  active  context  of  interest  is  the  real  subject  or 
referent ;  the  proposition  or  ready-made  judgment,  as  taken 
account  of  in  formal  logic,  is  in  this  relation  the  referatum. 
Not  the  proposition  as  interpreted  by  the  cognitive  moment, 
but  the  proposition  as  the  vehicle  of  the  active  meaning  at 
the  time,  is  the  symbol  of  the  judgment.  The  cold-storage 
proposition  was  a  judgment,  but  is  now  merely  an  object 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  141 

of  thought,  comparable  to  any  other  object,  such  as  gravi- 
tational relations  in  space. 

4.    The  Law  of  Finitude 

So  far  from  thought  being  infinite  in  character,  I  shall 
try  to  show  that  thought  or  truth  must  always  be  finite. 
We  have  seen  that  thought  is  in  nature  relational ;  that  it 
universally  means  the  active  selecting  and  assimilating  of 
a  datum  by  an  apperceptive  system  which  does  the  select- 
ing and  relating.  Now  both  the  content  selected  and  the 
system  within  which  it  is  to  be  related  or  defined  must  be 
finite  in  character.  We  must  generalize  from  certain  clear 
and  distinct  finite  characteristics.  I  will  use  geometry,  a 
purely  formal  science,  to  make  my  point  clear.  I  quote 
from  Russell  regarding  the  determination  of  points  and 
their  relations  :  "  Any  two  points  determine  a  unique  figure, 
called  a  straight  line,  and  three  in  general  determine  a  figure, 
the  plane.  Any  four  determine  a  corresponding  figure  of 
three  dimensions,  and  for  aught  that  appears  to  the  contrary 
the  same  may  be  true  of  any  number  of  points.  But  this 
process  comes  to  an  end,  sooner  or  later,  with  some  number 
of  points  which  determine  the  whole  of  space.  For  if  this 
were  not  the  case,  no  number  of  relations  of  a  point  to  a 
collection  of  given  points  could  ever  determine  its  relation 
to  fresh  points,  and  geometry  would  be  impossible." 1  And 
again  in  speaking  of  dimensions :  "  The  number  of  relations 
required  must  be  finite,  since  an  infinite  number  of  dimen- 
sions would  be  practically  impossible  to  determine."  2 

This  law  of  finitude  has  been  generalized  for  the  whole 
field  of  mathematical  science  by  so  great,  a  mathematician 

\<W!  G/Wv^ot  «*4-  X 

1 "  Foundations  of  Geometry,"  p.  152.    » 


142  Truth  and  Reality 

as  D.  Hilbert :  "  When  we  are  engaged  in  investigating 
the  foundations  of  a  science,  we  must  set  up  a  system  of 
axioms,  which  contains  an  exact  and  complete  description 
of  the  relations  subsisting  between  the  elementary  ideas  of 
that  science.  The  axioms  so  set  up  are  at  the  same  time 
the  definitions  of  those  elementary  ideas ;  and  no  statement 
within  the  realm  of  the  science  whose  foundation  we  are 
testing  is  held  to  be  correct,  unless  it  can  be  deduced  from 
those  axioms  by  a  finite  number  of  logical  steps."1 

That  we  always  base  our  concepts  or  laws  upon  the  ex- 
amination of  finite  facts  and  their  finite  relations  was  defi- 
nitely recognized  by  Aristotle :  "  If  the  kinds  of  causes 
had  been  infinite  in  number,  then  also  knowledge  would 
have  been  impossible ;  for  we  think  we  know,  only  when 
we  have  ascertained  all  the  causes,  but  that  which  is  in- 
finite by  addition  cannot  be  gone  through  in  finite  time."  z 
And  in  the  same  connection  he  shows  that  even  if  there 
existed  an  infinite,  the  concept  of  the  infinite  could  not  be 
infinite.  For  the  same  reason  both  Plato  and  Aristotle 
recognized  that  there  could  be  no  truth  of  absolute  flux  or 
absolute  chance.  It  is  only  flux  that  repeats  itself  under 
describable  conditions,  variety  with  finite  characteristics, 
that  can  be  reduced  to  science. 

To  be  sure  the  law  may  repeat  itself  in  an  endless  num- 
ber of  instances ;  there  may  be  no  last  term  in  the  series. 
Such  series  abound  in  mathematics.  But,  in  such  cases, 
it  is  not  the  potential  infinity  of  the  steps  which  constitutes 
knowledge.  Clearly,  a  generalization  from  enumeration 
would  be  a  contradiction,  if  we  assume  infinite  instances. 

1  Translation  by  Dr.  Mary  Winston  Newson  in  the  Bulletin  of  the  American 
Mathematical  Society,  July,  1902. 

2  End  of  Ch.  II,  Bk.  II,  "Metaphysics,"  translation  by  Ross. 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  143 

The  concept  of  the  series  is  based  upon  the  fact  that  the 
steps  repeat  themselves  according  to  certain  finite  charac- 
teristics or  laws.  It  is  this,  the  identical  or  universal  ele- 
ment, with  which  truth  is  concerned,  not  with  the  repetition. 
In  fact,  once  the  law  of  the  series  has  been  discovered,  the 
repetition  becomes  useless.  You  can  then  take  the  series 
as  completed.  There  would  be  no  virtue  in  repeating  the 
series,  i  +  \  +  \,  etc.,  after  discovering  its  limiting  term  or 
its  sum,  whichever  you  may  be  interested  in.  An  infinite 
number  is  contradictory,  because  « +  I  is  the  nature  of 
number.  This  law  is  based  upon  the  number  process  as 
actually  observed.  The  unpredictable  character  of  number, 
outside  of  its  general  law,  is  well  known,  because  in  each 
case  we  must  proceed  by  induction  from  individual  in- 
stances and  observe  their  relations. 

The  infinite,  in  the  case  of  thought,  arises  from  not  recog- 
nizing the  presuppositions  of  thought ;  for  example,  subject 
and  object.  The  infinite  reflective  series  does  not  solve  the 
problem.  It  can  only  bring  the  presupposition  involved  to 
light.  The  infinite  cannot  then  be  regarded  as  of  the  nature 
of  thought.  It  is  merely  a  result  of  reflecting  upon  the 
nature  of  a  reflective  system.  It  is  posited  by  thought  as  its 
logical  sport.  It  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  laws  or  validity 
of  thought.  It  shows  that  thought  is  dependent  upon  the 
larger  will  which  sets  the  game.  Knowing  knowledge  does 
not  mean  that  we  must  know  in  advance  of  knowledge,  but 
that  we  must  analyze  the  presuppositions  of  knowledge. 
It  is  the  circular  character  of  the  presuppositions  of  truth, 
looked  at  as  abstract  truth,  that  gives  rise  to  the  apparent 
infinity  of  truth.  But  the  infinity  is  only  apparent.  That 
the  law  of  identity  or  any  other  a  priori  postulate  is  episte- 
mologically  circular  is  as  clear  at  the  outset  as  it  would  be 


144  Truth  and  Reality 

after  endless  repetitions.  We  need  only  become  conscious 
of  its  a  priori  character  as  a  presupposition  of  truth.  To 
be  sure,  it  applies  to  itself  as  a  proposition  and  to  the  re- 
flection upon  this  application,  etc.,  but  nothing  is  gained  by 
such  a  repetition.  It  is  a  disease  of  language. 

The  infinity  of  Plato's  Parmenides  and  of  Bradley  is  a 
paradox  created  by  definition  —  by  taking  thought  as  ab- 
stractions, mutually  exclusive,  and  then  attempting  to  bring 
them  together.  In  the  infinite  of  the  Parmenides,  for  ex- 
ample, you  have  no  true  limit,  though  there  is  no  end  to 
the  series.  If  terms  are  like,  they  must  partake  of  or  be- 
long to  the  idea  of  absolute  likeness ;  but  in  this  case  the 
term  must  be  like  the  idea  and  the  idea  like  the  term ;  and 
this  likeness  must  be  due  to  their  partaking  in  an  idea  of 
likeness  and  so  on  to  infinity.  Otherness  would  do  as  well 
as  likeness.  In  fact  any  relation,  taken  as  an  abstraction, 
will  illustrate  how  contradictory  it  becomes.  Thus  the  one 
shows  itself  other  than  the  other,  etc.  In  Bradley,  you 
have  a  similar  infinite  as  regards  qualities  and  relations. 
Here,  too,  there  is  no  limit  or  progress  in  the  series.  If 
you  start  with  disparate,  independent  qualities,  then  any 
relation  which  tries  to  relate  them  must  have  something  in 
common  with  each  of  the  terms;  in  that  case  it  disrupts 
and  must  in  turn  be  related,  etc.,  ad  infinitum.1  But  the 
infinite  repetition  offers  no  solution.  It  simply  shows  that 
such  a  definition  of  qualities  makes  relations  impossible, 
which  ought  to  be  clear  at  the  outset. 

In  order  to  apply  the  conception  of  the  infinite  to  knowl- 
edge in  a  significant  way,  it  is  necessary  not  only  to  show 
that,  so  far  as  knowledge  is  concerned,  the  dualism  of  sub- 
ject and  object,  of  system  and  datum,  is  insuperable  and, 

1  For  a  recent  statement  of  Mr.  Bradley's  position,  see  Mind,  October,  1909, 
p.  494  ff. 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  145 

therefore,  that  no  finite  steps  can  solve  it,  but  it  is  neces- 
sary to  show  that  there  is  progress  toward  a  limit  and  what 
this  limit  is.  Now,  in  knowledge,  the  datum  to  be  organ- 
ized may  be  considered  as  capable  of  greater  and  greater 
systematization,  and  thus  growing  smaller  as  outstanding 
raw  material.  But  this  does  not  prove  that  knowledge  is 
infinite.  Further,  it  is  true  that  the  limit  of  the  thought 
process,  its  rationale,  cannot  be  reached  on  the  level  of 
thought,  for  though  all  other  data  were  organized,  all  other 
problems  solved  —  set  by  the  nature  of  the  content  or  by 
the  free  play  of  thought  —  when  the  last  surd  has  yielded 
up  its  enigma  to  the  progressive  system  of  knowledge, 
there  remains  the  problem  of  thought  itself.  Thought 
makes  itself  the  pure  content  of  its  own  reflections.  And 
here  it  discovers  a  limit  beyond  itself.  For  thought  can- 
not answer  the  question  :  '  why  thought  ? '  Or  why  does 
thought  have  this  constitution  and  no  other  ?  Why  this 
search  for  wholeness  ?  Or  stating  it  in  relational  terms  : 
Granting  that  we  may  be  able  to  weave  our  relations  into 
ever  larger  and  more  comprehensive  relations,  the  minor 
classes  into  still  larger  classes,  how  can  we  define  a  system 
of  relations  which  is  not  in  turn  relative  to  a  larger  system, 
a  class  which  is  not  itself  a  class  ?  Here  you  come  upon 
a  limit  of  the  process,  which  like  the  number  zero  or  the 
zero  of  quantity  lies  outside  the  process  itself,  viz.,  in  the 
purposive  will  which  chooses  to  realize  itself  in  this  way, 
chooses  this  form  of  activity  —  the  will  to  think.  But  there 
is  nothing  to  show  that  this  zero  lies  at  infinity.  It  is 
rather  the  purpose  within  which  thought  moves,  the  end 
for  which  it  exists.  Thought  has  reached  the  Canaan  of 
its  progress.  But,  like  Moses  of  old,  it  cannot  enter.  This 
is  the  land  of  faith. 


CHAPTER  VIII 

THE  POSTULATES  OF  TRUTH  CONTINUED 

IN  this  chapter  I  wish  to  discuss  some  proofs  of  the 
suggested  postulates.  I  also  want  to  show  their  place  in 
the  game  of  the  will,  and,  at  the  end,  offer  some  cautions 
as  against  some  present  tendencies.  But  after  the  long 
discussion  of  the  last  chapter,  it  may  be  well,  lest  we  for- 
get, to  restate  first  of  all  the  fundamental  presuppositions 
of  thought  as  I  understand  them. 

By  the  law  of  consistency,  I  understand  that  our  expe- 
rience of  reality,  whether  we  regard  it  from  the  point  of 
view  of  meanings  or  of  the  objects  intended,  must  possess 
such  identities  that  we  can  take  contents  over  again  and 
so  conceptualize  our  world,  whether  taken  as  individuals 
or  as  groups  of  individuals.  Thus  we  can  prepare  for  the 
future.  It  follows,  of  course,  that  if  we  must  thus  take  ex- 
perience, we  cannot  take  it  otherwise  in  the  same  respect, 
and  also  that  we  must  be  thorough  in  our  sorting,  if  we 
would  have  accurate  prediction,  i.e.,  our  contents  must  be 
disjunctively  arranged.  By  the  law  of  totality,  I  mean  that 
these  concepts  or  attributes,  these  part  definitions  of  our 
world,  must  be  seen  to  hang  together.  The  parts  of  reality 
must  make  such  differences  to  each  other,  directly  or  in- 
directly, as  to  constitute  a  dynamic  whole.  Atomism  and 
parallelism,  with  their  hydra-headed  forms,  make  the  ideal 
of  knowledge  impossible  at  the  very  outset.  Our  thoughts 

146 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  Continued  147 

must  belong  with  things  and  things  with  each  other  in  a 
dynamic  context  in  order  for  science  to  be  worth  while. 

By  the  subject-object  law,  or  the  law  of  duality,  I  mean 
that  thought  presupposes  the  unique  relation  of  an  active 
or  volitional  referent,  a  prospective  system  of  meanings, 
on  the  one  hand,  and  a  specific  object,  the  referatum, 
which  is  selected  by  this  cognitive  purpose,  on  the  other. 
The  subject-object  relation  is  distinct  from  other  functional 
relations  of  referent  and  referatum  through  the  volitional 
character  of  the  referent.  It  is  alive,  it  glows  with  inter- 
est. All  other  systems  of  relations,  whatever  their  specific 
meaning  may  be,  must  be  referred  to  this  living  subject  in 
order  to  have  systematic  value.  By  thought  being  '  repre- 
sentative '  I  mean  only  that  the  object,  for  purposes  of  truth, 
must  be  taken  over  into  this  systematic  context  of  active 
experience.  This  is  what  happens  in  the  process  of  judg- 
ment, the  simplest  form  of  which  is  symbolized  in  the 
proposition.  The  complete  truth  would  be  a  systematic, 
personal  experience  —  the  fulfillment  of  our  living  formal 
demands.  Such  an  ideal  is  Hegel's  absolute,  which  must 
be  held  valid  as  an  epistemological  ideal,  whatever  may  be 
its  claim  to  ontological  existence.  This  claim  I  do  not 
think  it  is  the  province  of  epistemology  to  settle. 

By  the  law  of  finitude,  I  understand  that  an  object,  in 
order  to  be  known,  must  be  capable  of  being  described  or 
identified  by  a  finite  number  of  marks  or  rules.  This  is 
true  even  of  the  concept  of  the  infinite,  which  I  agree  is 
hypothetically  possible.  The  infinite  series  is  defined,  how- 
ever, not  by  an  enumeration  of  its  instances,  which  is  im- 
possible, but  by  a  finite  rule  or  law.  In  truth,  as  in  our 
other  ideals,  we  demand  realization  or  completeness;  and 
this  is  possible  only  if  the  object,  however  infinite  in  its 


148  Truth  and  Reality 

instances,  submits  to  a  finite  law.  If  the  universe  itself  is 
an  infinite  process  with  creative  novelty,  then  truth  is  only 
in  part  realizable.  That  the  universe  is  such  is  not  a  case 
for  dogmatic  assumption,  but  to  be  proven  as  other  hy- 
potheses are  proven.  As  a  universe  of  absolute  chance 
would  make  truth  impossible,  the  attempt  to  prove  the 
existence  of  such  a  universe  would  be  contradictory. 

The  law  of  finitude  does  not  contradict  the  ideal  of  the 
completeness  of  truth.  If  the  absolute  should  prove  to  be 
a  valid  metaphysical  hypothesis,  we  must  suppose  that  the 
canons  which  hold  of  our  search  for  truth  hold  likewise 
for  the  absolute  experience,  including  the  law  of  finitude. 
For  suppose  that  the  absolute,  instead  of  generalizing 
from  finite  relations,  sees  truth  in  terms  of  infinite  relations, 
then  our  truth  would  bear  no  ratio  to  the  absolute.  With 
all  our  efforts  at  generalization,  we  should  never  approxi- 
mate any  nearer.  Our  research  would  be  futile  and  irrele- 
vant, and  we  should  land  in  the  dismal  abyss  of  agnosticism 
as  to  even  the  problematic  nature  of  truth,  which  of  course 
must  involve  the  existence  and  character  of  the  absolute 
itself.  In  other  words,  truth  would  have  entered  upon  the 
self-contradictory  task  of  attempting  to  define  the  (by  hy- 
pothesis) undefinable.  In  so  far  as  we  think  of  an  absolute 
truth,  we  must  think  it  as  the  completion  of  our  demands, 
not  as  a  violation  of  them. 


Coming  now  to  the  tests  of  our  postulates,  two  tests  have 
been  proposed :  (a)  Do  these  laws  presuppose  themselves  ? 
(b)  Are  they  presupposed  by  their  own  denial  ?  (a)  Do 
they  presuppose  themselves  ?  Take  the  law  of  consistency 
—  could  we  deal  with  the  meaning  of  consistency  unless 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  Continued  149 

we  could  take  it  as  the  same  ?  Clearly  not,  as  this  is  the 
only  way  in  which  we  can  define  it  or  deal  with  it  logically. 
If  you  take  again  the  law  of  totality,  here  presupposing  it- 
self would  mean  that  as  a  proposition  it  coheres  with  other 
propositions  of  experience,  thus  indicating  a  systematic 
whole.  And  this  is  certainly  assumed.  It  is  also  evident 
that  these  laws  presuppose  each  other.  The  law  of  totality 
must  have  a  consistent  meaning,  and  the  law  of  consistency 
must  cohere  with  other  propositions  into  a  systematic 
whole.  And  this  holds  of  the  other  postulates.  So  again 
with  the  subject-object  relation.  This  is  implied  in  itself. 
The  judgment  about  the  subject-object  relation  itself  pre- 
supposes the  subject-object  relation.  So  do  the  proposi- 
tions concerning  consistency  and  totality.  Likewise  must 
the  proposition  of  finitude  be  self-applicable  and  applicable 
to  the  other  postulates,  including  the  propositions  regard- 
ing identity,  totality  and  the  subject-object  form. 

If  you  take  again  the  second  test,  viz.,  that  they  must 
be  presupposed  by  their  own  denial,  this,  too,  is  met  by 
these  laws.  You  cannot  deny  the  law  of  consistency,  and 
still  have  the  proposition  of  consistency.  You  must  define 
what  you  mean  and  stick  to  it  for  the  purpose  of  the  argu- 
ment. Again,  you  cannot  deny  the  wholeness  of  human 
experience,  the  unity  of  our  world  of  thought,  because  in 
that  case  you  would  make  social  understanding  impossible ; 
and  presumably  you  argue  to  be  understood.  It  is  not 
necessary  to  stop  to  show  that  each  presupposition  holds 
for  the  other  —  that  the  denial  of  consistency,  in  regard  to 
the  proposition  of  totality,  must  imply  it,  and  that  the 
denial  of  the  unity,  or  social  character  of  our  world,  implies 
it,  when  you  try  to  argue  consistency.  A  denial  again  of 
the  subject-object  relation  clearly  presupposes  it,  for  the 


150  Truth  and  Reality 

judgment  of  denial  itself  takes  the  subject-object  form. 
And  if  you  deny  the  law  of  finitude,  you  imply  it,  for  the 
law  of  finitude  means  that  you  presuppose  finite  relations, 
and  it  can  be  shown  that  in  denying  the  law  of  finitude, 
your  judgment,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  involves  finite  relations. 

But  it  seems  to  me  that  only  the  argument,  which  proves 
that  you  cannot  think  at  all  without  implying  these  pos- 
tulates, establishes  a  universal  for  their  epistemological 
necessity.  This  you  cannot  get  by  showing  that  they  are 
actually  implied  in  any  given  judgments,  for  these  are  not 
exhaustive.  The  affirmative  implication  would  only  give 
you  a  particular  result,  not  a  universal.  To  establish  a 
universal  you  must  show,  not  only  that  the  judgment 
selected  implies  the  presuppositions  in  question,  but  that 
you  cannot  think,  make  any  judgment  whatsoever,  without 
presupposing  these  postulates.  That  you  show  that  they 
are  as  a  matter  of  fact  implied  in  their  own  prepositional 
statement,  and  that  their  denial  implies  them  in  the  case 
of  their  own  statement,  would  only  prove  a  particular 
application.  It  is  no  more  significant  that  they  imply 
themselves  or  that  their  denial  presupposes  them  in  their 
own  statement  than  to  suppose  that  such  is  the  case  in 
regard  to  some  other  proposition.  It  would  not  prove 
that  they  must  hold  in  the  case  of  all  propositions. 

To  make  them  universal,  we  can  do  one  of  two  things. 
We  can  assume  them  as  conventions  or  we  can  show  that, 
in  the  actual  social  procedure  of  thought,  there  can  be  no 
negative  instance  without  making  truth  impossible,  which 
would  show  that  they  must  hold  for  all  cases  of  truth. 
In  the  former  case  we  can  meet  with  no  negative  instance, 
because  we  have  by  definition  forestalled  any  such  instance, 
just  as,  when  we  posit  a  space  of  zero  curvature,  we  can- 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  Continued  151 

not,  for  the  purpose,  meet  with  a  case  which  is  not  of  that 
character.  But  as  thought  is  an  actual  constitution,  we 
are  not  at  liberty  to  posit  at  will.  Rather,  as  in  the  case 
of  number,  must  we  discover  what  the  ideal  constitution  of 
thought  is.  The  second  method,  therefore,  is  the  one  we 
must  choose.  And  here  we  must  show,  not  only  that  the 
law  holds  in  a  particular  instance,  as  in  the  case  of  its  own 
statement,  but  that  there  can  be  no  instance  in  which  it 
does  not  hold. 

Now  suppose  any  instance,  n,  in  which  the  law  in  ques- 
tion does  not  hold.  Take  the  law  of  consistency.  Then 
in  such  a  case  truth  is  impossible.  For  in  order  for  truth 
to  be  possible,  it  will  be  seen  that  we  must  be  able  to  take 
our  meaning  as  the  same.  Otherwise  there  can  be  no 
definition  or  argument.  So  in  regard  to  any  of  the  other 
laws.  And  the  consciousness  that  there  can  be  no  truth, 
if  the  law  does  not  hold,  makes  explicit  the  law.  If  it  is 
objected  that  this  is  a  circular  process  and  not  a  proof,  I 
would  entirely  agree.  The  process,  however,  brings  out 
the  implication,  shows  us  the  already  implied  necessity  of 
the  postulates  for  all  our  thinking.  And  this  making  ex- 
plicit what  is  implicit  is  all  the  demonstration  of  which  the 
presuppositions  of  thought  are  capable. 

But  does  this  mean  that  these  presuppositions  are  also  onto- 
logically  necessary  ?  That  they  require  no  proof  as  regards 
their  real  validity,  in  the  actual  procedure  of  experience  ? 
Our  ability  to  acquire  knowledge,  to  meet  our  world  of 
facts  on  such  a  basis,  must  here  be  the  guarantee  and  the 
only  guarantee.  And  every  partial  success  makes  the  law 
in  so  far  valid,  though  a  complete  success  alone  could  be 
a  complete  vindication.  If  truth  is  found  to  be  actually 
possible,  then,  in  so  far,  the  presuppositions  are  onto- 


152  Truth  and  Reality 

logically  valid.  The  mere  assumption  of  ideality,  totality, 
subject-object  or  finitude  does  not  make  them  existentially 
valid.  If  we  are  to  know,  they  must  hold  for  our  universe 
as  experienced.  While  they  are  a  priori  and  necessary 
postulates  from  the  point  of  view  of  formal  knowledge, 
from  the  point  of  view  of  reality  they  must  be  treated  as 
hypotheses  to  be  verified  in  the  procedure  of  experience. 
It  is  not  inconceivable  that  a  world  should  exist  in  which 
the  postulates  of  consistency,  totality,  subject-object  and 
finitude  would  have  no  applicability.  But  it  is  also  true  that 
in  such  a  world  truth  would  be  impossible.  In  this  there  is 
no  contradiction,  since  it  is  from  the  point  of  view  of  a  uni- 
verse where  truth  is  admittedly  possible  that  we  make  the 
judgment  of  the  impossibility  of  truth  in  a  world  where  its 
presuppositions  do  not  hold.  If  you  argue  truth,  you  of 
course  presuppose  the  possibility  of  truth.  The  best  refu- 
tation of  the  skeptic  who  denies  that  there  is  agreement, 
etc.,  is  the  method  of  Socrates  that  we  do  understand  each 
other.  If  there  are  wholly  disparate  worlds,  they  at  least 
do  not  concern  us.  If  the  above  postulates  are  formally 
true,  you  can  easily  conceive  a  world  in  which  truth  is  not 
possible  by  dropping  one  or  more  of  the  postulates. 

But  there  can  be  no  a  priori  valid  metaphysical  postulates. 
The  only  possible  ontological  necessities  are  the  necessities 
of  facts  —  of  the  conditions  which  we  must  meet  in  realiz- 
ing our  purposes,  what  reality  must  be  taken  as  in  order  to 
satisfy  the  demands  of  the  will.  Such  necessities,  it  must 
be  admitted,  are  in  large  part  hypothetical,  owing  to  the 
fragmentariness  of  our  knowledge. 

On  the  other  hand,  it  is  not  conceivable  that  in  a  uni- 
verse where  truth  is  admitted  as  an  ontological  fact,  truth 
could  also  be  looked  upon  as  an  accident  —  an  accidental 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  Continued  153 

variation  of  a  biological  process  or  any  other  accident.  A 
universe  in  which  truth  exists  must  make  it  reasonable  that 
truth  can  exist.  There  can  be  no  evolutionary  epistemol- 
ogy  in  the  sense  of  biological  chance.  And  the  question 
of  the  validity  of  the  above  postulates  is  quite  independent 
of  any  theory  of  biological  evolution. 

Is  there  any  difference  as  regards  the  primacy  of  these 
postulates,  —  for  example,  the  law  of  consistency  and  the  law 
of  totality  ?  Is  the  former  self-evident  in  a  sense  the  latter 
is  not*?  Is  it  possible  in  each  case  to  conceive  the  oppo- 
site ?  I  believe  it  is.  If  it  is  possible  to  conceive  a  uni- 
verse existing  in  compartments,  disparate  systems,  which 
do  not  touch  each  other  at  any  point,  so  it  is  also  possible 
to  conceive  a  universe  of  flux  in  which  there  is  no  identity, 
and  in  which,  therefore,  no  predication  is  possible.  One  is 
no  more  a  fortunate  circumstance  than  the  other.1  But 
while  we  can  conceive  such  a  world,  we  cannot  conceive 
thought  in  such  a  world.  It  is  also  conceivable  that  a 
world  of  dreamy  absorption  or  even  of  no  experience  might 
exist.  In  such  a  world  there  would  be  no  subject-object 
relation,  but  neither  would  there  be  any  thought.  So  a 
world  of  infinite  dimensions  is  conceivable,  but  thought  is 
not  conceivable  in  such  a  world. 

There  can  be  no  priority  as  regards  the  presuppositions 
of  thought.  If  there  were,  they  would  not  be  universal 
presuppositions.  Each  must  hold  for  all  thought,  includ- 
ing itself  as  well  as  the  other  presuppositions.  Each  is 
circular  in  character  or  incapable  of  proof  so  far  as  episte- 
mology  is  concerned.  It  is  this  circular  character  of  the 
form  of  truth  which  gives  rise  to  the  paradox  which  was 
already  noted  by  Plato  in  the  Theaetetus,  viz.,  that  a  logical 

1  Contrast  Lotze's  treatment,  "  Logic"  (English  trans.),  Vol.  I,  pp.  94-96. 


154  Truth  and  Reality 

definition  of  knowledge  is  impossible,  because  in  defin- 
ing knowledge  we  cannot  avoid  using  knowledge  in  the 
predicate,  as  when  we  use  the  definition  suggested  by 
"  some  one  "  that  "  knowledge  is  right  opinion  with  rational 
definition  or  explanation."  To  have  a  right  opinion  and 
be  able  to  give  the  reasons  for  it,  which  is  the  very  essence 
of  the  syllogism,  certainly  seems  a  satisfactory  definition  of 
knowledge.  And  it  took  the  genius  of  Plato  to  discover 
that  this  definition  was  really  circular,  for  right  opinion 
with  explanation  means  "  right  opinion  with  knowledge  of 
difference  "  ;  and  so  we  have  presupposed  the  very  thing 
we  were  to  define  —  the  form  of  knowledge.  This  circular 
or  self-applicable  character  of  the  definition  of  knowledge 
we  have  now  come  to  accept.  But  we  must  also  come  to 
realize  that  this  circular  character  is  in  no  way  remedied 
by  an  infinite  series  of  hypothetical  reflective  acts,  to  the 
effect  that  we  know  that  we  know,  and  again,  that  we 
know  that  we  know  that  we  know,  etc.  Such  a  series 
solves  nothing.  It  merely  emphasizes  the  circular  charac- 
ter of  the  form  of  thought.  The  truth  of  truth  cannot  be 
proved  a  priori.  It  can  only  be  proved  by  its  convenience 
in  ministering  to  the  will,  which  sets  the  game  of  thought. 

II 

And  now  a  word  as  regards  the  relation  of  the  will  to 
thought.  For  finite  purposes  it  is  convenient  to  regard 
the  will  as  a  larger  genus  than  thought.  While  thought 
is  the  systematic  activity  of  the  will  in  its  higher  develop- 
ment, not  all  will  is  systematic,  and  in  this  sense  is  non-ra- 
tional. Its  rationality,  at  any  rate,  is  prospective,  not  actual. 
In  our  finite  sphere  there  seems  to  be  error,  due  to  false 
assent  or  failure  to  assent  to  a  supposed  truth.  Such  must 


TJie  Postulates  of  Truth  Continued  155 

seem  to  the  absolute  idealist  my  failure  to  subscribe  to  his 
assumption  that  reality  is  an  organic  experience.  If  the 
logic  is  truly  coercive,  my  failure  to  assent  must  be  a  cer- 
tain blindness  on  the  part  of  the  will.  It  is  the  old  ques- 
tion whether  virtue  can  be  reduced  to  mere  knowledge,  or 
whether  we  must  not  also  assume  a  certain  willingness  to 
accept  the  ideal,  whether  theoretical  or  practical.  The 
will  must  furnish  the  goal  and  motive  of  thought.  Else 
thought  would  move  in  a  vacuum.  If  the  will,  however, 
chooses  to  think,  it  must  do  so  in  accordance  with  certain 
rules.  It  is  this  deliberation  according  to  certain  rules, 
whether  the  aim  be  merely  formal  agreement  or  also  per- 
ceptual termination,  which  constitutes  the  difference  be- 
tween thinking  and  volition  in  general.  To  the  fully 
organized  will,  such  thinking  has  become  the  normal  activ- 
ity. The  will,  too,  may  divest  itself  of  its  practical,  bio- 
logical interest  and  pursue  science  as  a  sport  —  a  game 
furnishing  its  own  logical  and  esthetic  satisfaction  apart 
from  its  survival  value. 

We  may  sum  up  the  place  of  thought  in  the  economy  of 
life  by  saying  that  thought  is  an  activity  of  the  will,  pre- 
determined as  regards  its  form  by  certain  presuppositions 
which  are  posited  by  the  will  to  think.  It  is  not  the  only 
activity  of  the  will.  The  will  may  be  instinctive  in  its  ac- 
tivity, it  may  be  perceptual,  it  may  be  guided  by  concrete 
images,  it  may  dream.  But  when  the  will  sets  itself  the 
task  of  thinking,  whether  for  purposes  of  practical  neces- 
sity or  for  the  enjoyment  afforded  by  the  game  of  thinking 
itself,  the  will  accepts  or  postulates  certain  norms,  a  con- 
stitution of  thought.  These  it  postulates  in  a  very  dif- 
ferent sense  from  n  dimensional  or  negative  curvature 
space,  which  it  postulates  simply  from  choice  for  the  sake 


156  Truth  and  Reality 

of  a  particular  thought  activity.  The  laws  of  thought  the 
will  must  postulate  in  order  to  think  at  all.  The  only  way 
the  will  can  choose  not  to  be  bound  by  the  necessities  of 
thought  is  not  to  think.  The  will  sets  itself  the  task  of 
the  conscious  definition  of  its  own  purpose  by  means 
of  concepts,  and  it  wills  to  pursue  this  process  in  accord- 
ance with  certain  formal  conditions,  which  it  acknowledges 
as  binding  for  the  purpose,  viz.,  the  laws  of  thought. 
Plato's  view  in  the  Parmenides  that  we  cannot  know  the 
absolute  norms  is  mistaken.  They  are  few  and  easily  de- 
fined. Such  norms  are  for  thought,  ideals,  limits,  faiths 
in  the  attainability  of  truth,  but  as  such  they  provide  a 
goal  for  our  striving,  and  in  a  formal  way  at  least,  they 
must  be  the  warp  of  our  thinking.  They  are  not  gen- 
eralizations, but  presupposed  as  conditions  by  all  general- 
izations. 

Does  thought,  then,  transcend  itself  ?  No,  I  should 
rather  say,  thought  is  transcended  by  the  will  or  faith 
which  sets  it,  and  the  demands  of  the  constitution  which 
it  must  meet.  Faith  sets  the  problem  of  truth  —  the 
search  for  unity.  Faith,  too,  promises  the  solution,  sets 
the  limit  of  the  process,  demands  that  there  shall  be  form 
or  unity.  Otherwise  thought  would  be  an  aimless  play 
with  contradictions.  Thought,  thus  inspired,  succeeds  in 
approximations,  pragmatic  formulas,  which  are  as  good  as 
true,  even  if  approximations.  But  thought  itself  —  i.e., 
the  process  of  judgment,  conception  and  inference  —  is 
machinery  in  the  service  of  faith.  Thought  is  relative  — 
relative  to  the  realization  of  the  will,  its  work  and  play  — 
relative,  as  every  function  must  be,  to  life  as  a  whole. 
This  relativity  of  thought  is  shown  whether  we  examine 
its  subject-object  form  or  its  relational  content.  We  can- 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  Continued  157 

not  deal  with  thought  as  an  abstraction  without  thought 
becoming  paradoxical  or  circular. 

Thus  to  deal  with  thought  as  relative  to  life  as  a  whole 
is  not  assuming  that  the  universe  is  irrational.  That  must 
be  determined  by  the  outcome  of  thought,  not  by  a  priori 
prejudices.  The  very  existence  of  the  postulates  of  thought 
and  the  success  thought  has  had  in  their  application  shows 
that  the  universe  in  part  lends  itself  to  thought's  formula- 
tion. That  it  does  so  altogether  is  obviously  a  faith. 
Whether  such  a  faith  turns  out  to  be  absolutely  true  or 
not,  we  shall  still  hold  to  thought  for  its  convenience  in 
dealing  with  our  world,  for  its  part-truth,  its  prospective 
value.  There  are  constancies  which  we  can  seize  upon  in 
the  stream  of  experience  and  thus  regulate  our  conduct. 
Nature  not  only  favors  thought  as  regards  capacity  and 
demand,  but  it  puts  a  premium  upon  thought  as  regards 
survival.  What  reality  must  be  taken  as  in  the  last  analy- 
sis must  be  the  outcome  of  the  truth  experiment. 

The  impulse  to  think  must  not  be  looked  upon  as  an  ar- 
tificial appendage,  tacked  on  to  life  without  any  relation  to 
its  fitness  or  needs.  Rather  it  is  a  normal  expression  of 
life  as  it  unfolds  its  growth  series,  as  the  sex  instinct  is  a 
normal  expression  of  life  and  its  necessities,  however  early 
or  late  it  may  awaken.  The  universe  is  so  constituted  as 
to  make  through  us  such  demands  upon  itself  for  the  larg- 
est life.  And  that  is  all  we  know.  That  truth  is  possible 
and  that  truth  is  worth  while  is  a  faith  prior  to  truth  and 
justified  by  its  consequences  to  the  life  process  of  which  it 
is  a  part.  The  ego  wills  to  think  —  both  because  it  is  prac- 
tically useful  and  because  it  provides  ideal  sport — but  in 
willing  to  think  it  also  wills  to  accept  the  formal  conditions 
without  which  thinking  would  become  impossible.  The 


158  Truth  and  Reality 

will  can  refuse  to  think.  In  that  case  it  can  run  riot  as  it 
pleases,  determined  by  no  law  except  the  determinations 
of  pleasure  and  pain.  But  if  the  will  chooses  to  think, 
then  it  also  chooses  certain  laws  of  procedure.  Thought 
itself  must  accept  its  own  existence  and  nature  as  a  fact. 
It  cannot  transcend  its  own  constitution  a  priori  or  as 
thought. 

These  postulates  I  hold,  indeed,  to  be  true  for  thinking, 
but  thinking,  while  of  a  tissue  with  reality,  is  thin  compared 
with  the  thickness  of  the  process  of  life.  We  can,  indeed, 
find  our  way  from  part  to  part,  in  time  and  space,  by 
thought.  It  is  convenient  to  think.  And  thinking  is  true 
to  all  it  can  hold.  But  it  is  a  sieve,  which  part  of  reality 
necessarily  runs  through.  "  Ever  not  quite  "  must  be  the 
qualification  of  thinking  as  compared  with  the  fullness  of 
concrete  reality.  And  the  "  not  quite  "  is  usually  the  big 
part  and  the  thinking  a  mere  edge. 

Ill 

Lastly,  I  want  to  offer  a  caution  or  two  :  First  it  is  well 
to  remember,  in  spite  of  the  mystical  tendencies  of  to-day, 
that  truth  is  an  adjective  of  thinking  and  has  no  meaning 
outside  of  systematic  judgment.  We  cannot  speak  of 
mystical  appreciation,  any  more  than  of  perceptual  imme- 
diacy, as  truth.  Truth  is  always  an  active  sorting  of  reality 
as  experienced.  This  need  not  mean,  however,  a  trans- 
muting of  reality  as  first  experienced.  The  sorting  does 
not  necessarily  alter  the  qualities  it  sorts.  If  so,  there  is 
no  way,  mediate  or  immediate,  to  truth. 

In  the  second  place,  it  is  not  fair  to  charge  the  thought 
process  with  the  contradictions  arising  from  our  conceptual 
assumptions.  Rather  overhaul  the  assumptions.  Men 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  Continued  159 

like  Spencer  and  Bradley  have  charged  thought  with  in- 
consistency and  bankruptcy  because  of  the  ready-made 
assumptions  with  which  they  have  started.  It  may  be 
there  are  ways  of  conceiving  space,  time,  etc.,  which  are 
not  contradictory. 

Thirdly,  I  cannot  agree  that  thought  is  the  only  final 
way  of  evaluating  life.  "  There  is  not  only  one  way  to 
the  realm  of  the  gods,"  to  quote  an  old  Viking  poem. 
Esthetic  appreciation  furnishes  another  evaluation  of  life 
which  cannot  be  reduced  to  terms  of  thought,  and  some 
who  have  grown  weary  of  the  arduous  path  of  truth  have 
decided  to  pitch  their  tents  in  the  restful  oasis  of  beauty. 
Others  again  have  found  in  our  sense  of  duty,  in  the  urg- 
ing of  conscience,  the  key  which  unlocks  reality.  Tem- 
perament, no  doubt,  has  a  great  deal  to  do  with  our 
preference  here.  But  what  must  not  be  lost  sight  of  is 
that  there  are  different  ways  of  reaching  the  final  signifi- 
cance of  life ;  and  if  we  are  not  able  to  drive  the  triple  team 
of  values  abreast,  we  must  at  least  appreciate  that  our 
preference  does  not  annul  distinctions  —  does  not  make  es- 
thetic appreciation  truth.  The  failure  to  distinguish  these 
types  of  evaluation,  or  using  thought  loosely  to  stand  for 
each  and  all  indifferently,  has  been  a  serious  weakness  of 
Hegelianism.  They  may  all  be  harmonious  and  comple- 
mentary in  human  nature  as  realized.  Identical  they  can- 
not be.  But  while  thought  is  not  all  of  life,  and  must  be 
understood  in  relation  to  life  as  a  whole,  it  is  the  only  way 
in  which  we  can,  in  the  last  analysis,  realize  the  truth  of 
life,  its  scales  of  values.  And  we  must  be  awake  part  of 
the  time  to  estimate  the  significance  of  perception  or  of 
mystical  appreciation.  Whether  we  regard  it  more  im- 
portant to  be  awake  in  order  that  we  may  sleep  or  to  sleep 


160  Truth  and  Reality 

in  order  that  we  may  be  awake,  is  likely  to  be  decided  on 
the  basis  of  temperament.  Both  sleeping  and  waking,  ap- 
preciation and  thought,  in  the  end,  must  be  estimated  from 
their  rhythmic  place  in  life  as  a  whole.  Certainly  the 
sleeping  states,  however  blissful,  have  no  truth  except  as 
taken  up  into  the  woof  of  the  waking  states. 

The  main  epistemological  difficulty  as  between  my  ideal- 
istic colleagues  and  myself  seems  to  be  that  I  cannot  ac- 
cept the  ontological  absolute  as  a  postulate,  but  insist  on 
proof.  I  admit  that  my  incredulity  here  is  due  to  my 
metaphysical  leanings  ;  but  I  do  not  see  any  good  reason, 
in  any  case,  why  we  should  assume  a  metaphysical  theory 
as  a  condition  of  our  search  for  truth.  Ought  not  our 
method  to  be  neutral  enough  so  as  not  to  prejudice  the 
results  of  the  search  ?  Is  it  not  better  to  start  with  the 
common  conciousness,  with  its  dualism  of  thought  and 
things,  and  to  follow  the  dialectic  of  the  thought  process, 
as  it  attempts  to  master  its  more  or  less  stubborn  world  ? 
This  would  seem  to  be  Hegel's  own  procedure.  If  the 
necessities  of  the  truth  process  should  lead  in  the  direction 
of  an  idealistic  absolute,  I  hope  I  shall  be  honest  enough 
to  accept  the  implications  without  abandoning  the  truth. 
That  I  cannot  do  so  now  is  due  to  no  lack  of  respect  for 
my  idealistic  colleagues,  among  whom  I  number  my  friend 
and  teacher,  Josiah  Royce.  Idealism  certainly  has  made 
the  only  thorough-going  attempt,  up  to  date,  to  give  a 
systematic  account  of  experience.  Its  critics  seem  to  have 
lived  mostly  on  the  weaknesses  of  idealism. 

I  insist,  however,  that  the  hypothesis  of  the  universe  as 
an  absolute  experience  cannot  be  settled  a  priori.  It  must 
come  as  a  result  of  our  success  in  applying  our  logical 
ideals.  Certainly  the  universe  is  in  part  rational  experi- 


The  Postulates  of  Truth  Continued  161 

ence,  for  human  thinking  is  an  intrinsic  part  of  the  uni- 
verse. In  part,  too,  we  have  been  successful  in  applying 
logical  categories  to  the  infra-human  world.  And  in  so 
far  it  cannot  be  regarded  as  irrational,  whether  it  is  non- 
rational  or  not.  We  find  it  convenient  in  any  case  to  dis- 
tinguish, for  purposes  of  conduct,  between  the  thinking 
and  the  non-thinking  world  and  to  treat  the  latter  as  means 
to  the  former  as  end.  I  have  faith  in  a  higher  conscious- 
ness than  the  human  as  the  fulfilment  of  our  fragmentary 
insight  and  "  the  final  cause  "  of  the  evolutionary  process. 
But  I  do  not  see  any  leading  toward  this  mind  in  the  infra- 
human  world  —  the  world  of  the  stone  and  the  amoeba.  I 
must  rather  seek  it  hi  the  supra-human  reaches  as  the  goal 
of  our  ideal  striving.  While  mystical  and  esthetic  intuition 
may  seem  to  furnish  some  of  us  a  very  intimate  acquaint- 
ance with  such  a  world,  I  cannot  see  that  such  a  faith 
exempts  reason  from  dealing  with  it  as  an  hypothesis  and 
from  testing  it  as  any  hypothesis  is  tested,  through  its  suc- 
cess in  simplifying  and  guiding  experience.  I  do  not  deny 
the  possibility  of  the  idealistic  absolute.  There  is  certainly 
nothing  contradictory  in  the  conception  of  such  a  complete, 
systematic  experience.  On  the  contrary,  it  must  always 
figure  as  .an  epistemological  ideal,  even  if  not  an  ontologi- 
cal  assumption. 


PART  III 
THE  CRITERION  OF  TRUTH 


CHAPTER   IX 

FROM  PROTAGORAS  TO  WILLIAM  JAMES 

IN  this  chapter  I  wish  to  give  a  brief  historic  orientation 
of  pragmatism.  In  later  chapters  I  will  take  up  the  prag- 
matic criterion,  as  I  understand  it,  more  in  detail. 


It  is  a  long  stretch  historically  from  Protagoras  to  Wil- 
liam James.  Yet  critics  have  not  been  slow  in  pointing  out 
the  similarity  between  the  doctrine  of  the  founder  of  an- 
cient humanism  and  the  pragmatic  movement  of  to-day.  In 
this  the  critics  have  spoken  truer  than  they  knew.  For 
historical  research  has  now  made  clear  that  Protagoras  was 
no  subjectivist,  as  was  so  long  supposed,  from  a  misinter- 
pretation of  Plato,  but  a  genuine  empiricist.  I  agree  in  the 
main  with  Gomperz's  results  in  his  treatment  of  Protagoras.1 
But  I  believe  that  these  results,  with  proper  interpretation, 
can  be  derived  from  Plato,  especially  the  Theaetetus,  which 
Gomperz  discards.  On  the  basis  of  this  new  interpretation 
of  Protagoras,  we  may  indeed  adopt  the  first  sentence  of 
Protagoras's  work  on  truth  as  a  fair  epitome  of  modern 
pragmatism :  "  Man  is  the  measure  of  all  things,  of  those 
which  are  that  they  are  and  of  those  which  are  not  that 
they  are  not."  Or  to  use  Goethe's  paraphrase  :  "  We  may 
watch  nature,  measure  her,  reckon  her,  weigh  her,  etc.,  as 
we  will.  It  is  yet  but  our  measure  and  weight,  since  man 
is  the  measure  of  things." 

1 "  Greek  Thinkers,"  Vol.  I,  pp.  438-475. 
'65 


1 66  Truth  and  Reality 

It  is  a  commonplace  now  that  human  nature  must  be  the 
starting  point  for  all  our  theories  concerning  reality.  We 
can  only  speak  of  those  things  as  existent  that  make  a  dif- 
ference to  human  nature,  either  directly  as  immediate  ex- 
perience or  indirectly  as  assumptions  needed  to  account 
for  such  immediate  experience  as  our  perception  with  its 
microscopes  and  telescopes  furnishes  us.  If  things  make 
no  difference  directly  or  indirectly,  perceptually  or  con- 
ceptually, to  human  nature,  they  are  mere  fictions,  belong 
in  a  world  of  centaurs  and  mermaids.  At  any  rate  we 
cannot  say  whether  they  are  or  are  not. 

And  what  is  true  in  regard  to  the  existence  of  things 
holds  equally  in  regard  to  their  properties  and  values. 
These,  too,  must  be  regarded  as  included  in  Protagoras's 
thesis,  for  the  doctrine  of  the  functional  relation  of  quali- 
ties and  values  to  human  nature  is  distinctly  attributed  to 
Protagoras  in  the  dialogue  by  that  name.  The  doctrine  of 
the  relativity  of  values  Protagoras  inherited  from  Heracli- 
tus,  who  showed  that  values  depend  upon  the  relation  of 
the  object  to  the  specific  will,  whether  that  of  ass,  or  ox, 
or  fish,  or  hog,  or  surgeon.  "Asses  would  rather  have 
straw  than  gold."  1  Relativity  of  values  to  the  will  does 
not  mean  subjectivity  of  values.  We  can  predict  values 
for  definite  wills.  We  know  what  the  ox  and  ass  want,  un- 
der definite  conditions.  We  must  judge  the  values  and 
properties  of  things,  as  well  as  their  existence,  from  the 
differences  they  make  to  human  nature  in  varying  contexts. 
Things  are  colored,  extended,  sweet  or  bitter  ;  they  are 
pleasant  or  unpleasant,  beautiful  or  ugly,  because  they  be- 
long in  a  context  with  conscious  human  nature.  Things 
or  individuals  have  those  properties  that  we  must  acknow- 
1  See  Fragments  51-58,  Burnet,  "Early  Greek  Philosophers,"  p.  137. 


From  Protagoras  to    William  James  167 

ledge  in  order  to  adjust  ourselves  to  our  environment  or 
realize  our  purposes.  To  speak  of  a  property  that  makes 
no  difference  directly  or  indirectly  to  human  nature,  is  to 
mistake  fancy  for  reality.  There  is  no  property  in  the 
abstract,  no  good  in  general.  In  this  Socrates  and  Pro- 
tagoras agree. 

So  far  modern  pragmatism  and  Protagoras  are  at  one. 
They  are  at  one,  too,  in  applying  this  criterion  to  all  types 
of  existence,  physical  or  pyschological,  natural  or  super- 
natural. Knowledge  everywhere  must  be  based  upon 
evidence  as  furnished  through  human  experience.  "  In  re- 
spect to  the  gods,"  says  Protagoras,  "  I  am  unable  to  know 
either  that  they  are  or  that  they  are  not,  for  there  are  many 
obstacles  to  such  knowledge,  above  all,  the  obscurity  of  the 
matter  and  the  life  of  man,  in  that  it  is  so  short."  We 
must  know  the  existence  and  properties  of  the  supernatural 
as  we  know  nature  —  by  evidence.  To  be  sure,  in  our  con- 
ception of  experience  as  race  experience  we  are  able  to  eke 
out  somewhat  further  the  evidence  that  Protagoras  found 
insufficient  in  individual  experience.  Individual  experi- 
ence is  supplemented  by  further  historic  experience  in  try- 
ing out  the  hypothesis.  But  human  nature  still  remains 
the  measure. 

We  know,  too,  that  what  differences  shall  exist  for  us 
vary  vastly  with  the  efficiency  of  our  tools,  perceptual  and 
conceptual.  The  rings  of  Saturn  or  the  properties  of 
radium  make  a  difference  to  human  nature  only  with 
improved  tools,  not  only  in  the  way  of  telescopes  and  micro- 
scopes, but  in  the  way  of  scientific  conceptions.  Consider- 
ing the  limitations  of  our  powers  of  perception  as  compared 
with  the  complexity  of  the  objects,  this  leaves  sufficient 
room  for  scientific  agnosticism.  This  agnosticism,  how- 


1 68  Truth  and  Reality 

ever,  is  one  of  degree,  not  of  kind.  To  the  extent  that  we 
know  the  properties  of  things,  we  must  believe  that  they 
are  such  as  we  must  take  them.  To  say,  then,  that  all  we 
know  must  be  known  from  the  difference  it  makes  to  human 
experience  must  be  accepted  as  an  evident,  even  if  tauto- 
logical, truism.  Tautology  it  seemed  even  to  Aristotle. 
But,  if  it  is  logical  tautology,  it  marks,  both  in  ancient  and 
modern  times,  decidedly  a  new  psychological  step  in  the 
development  of  human  consciousness,  a  step  so  striking 
that  its  recent  re-discovery  has  been  well-nigh  epoch- 
making. 

II 

If  human  nature  is  to  be  taken  as  the  starting  point 
and  measure,  we  must  first  of  all  define  human  nature. 
Here  again  the  problem  is  old,  and  we  must  strive  to  learn 
from  the  past.  Not  to  orient  ourselves  with  reference  to 
the  past  is  to  talk  like  drunken  men  or  men  suddenly  awake. 
A  great  deal  of  confusion  and  misunderstanding  could  have 
been  obviated  in  the  recent  pragmatic  discussion  and  a 
great  deal  of  energy  economized  on  both  sides,  if  those 
taking  part  in  it  had  taken  pains  to  read  Plato's  Theaetetus. 

If  things  exist  and  are  what  they  are  because  of  the 
differences  they  make  to  human  nature,  then  what  is  hu- 
man nature  or  in  what  respect  must  they  make  a  difference  ? 
Protagoras  in  setting  the  new  program,  so  revolutionary 
in  philosophic  investigation,  failed,  so  far  as  we  know,  to 
define  human  nature.  This  failure  has  probably  a  twofold 
root.  One  root  is  the  inadequacy  of  his  psychological 
tools.  Thought  and  perception  were  not  as  yet  clearly 
differentiated.  This  we  can  see  from  the  fragments  of 
Empedocles.  Thought  and  perception  here  alike  depend 


From  Protagoras  to    William  James  169 

upon  effluences  and  the  action  of  like  upon  like.  The 
concept  has  not  yet  been  discovered.  This  is  the  immortal 
contribution  of  Socrates  and  Plato.  It  is  this  lack  of  dis- 
tinction that  Plato  feels  when  he  says  in  the  Theaetetus 
that  "  perception  and  sight  and  knowledge  are  supposed  to 
be  the  same." 

But  another,  and  still  more  significant  reason,  we  find 
in  the  problem  which  Protagoras  sets  himself.  We  learn 
from  Porphyry  that  Protagoras  hi  his  great  work  on 
"Truth"  directed  his  shafts  against  the  Eleatics.1  In  other 
words,  the  bitter  struggle  of  Protagoras,  as  of  his  modern 
successors,  was  with  the  intellectualists.  Only  the  Eleatics 
were  no  milk-and-water  intellectualists.  They  had  the 
courage  of  their  convictions.  In  Parmenides,  the  venerable 
founder  of  the  school,  they  had  their  unequivocal  platform  : 
"  For  it  is  the  same  thing  that  can  be  thought  and  that 
can  be."  Thought  coerces  being.  Zeno  had  riddled  the 
world  of  perception  with  his  brilliant  dialectic,  and  Melissos 
had  drawn  the  consequences  of  the  logic  of  his  predeces- 
sors :  "  Wherefore  it  ensueth  that  we  neither  see  nor  know 
the  many."  It  was  this  arrogant  confidence  in  a  priori 
thought  and  contempt  for  sense  that  Protagoras  set  him- 
self to  refute. 

We  cannot  wonder,  then,  that  Protagoras  seemed  to  his 
critics  to  neglect  thought  and  to  place  a  one-sided  emphasis 
upon  the  immediate.  Here  again  history  has  repeated 
itself.  But  it  seems  less  of  an  omission  when  we  remem- 
ber that  there  was  no  need  of  emphasizing  the  importance  of 
thought  so  far  as  the  Eleatic  intellectualists  were  concerned. 
Knowledge,  Protagoras  insists,  must  proceed  from  evidence. 
It  cannot  be  produced  in  vacua  by  means  of  mere  logical 
i  Gomperz, "  Greek  Thinkers,"  Vol.  I,  p.  450. 


170  Truth  and  Reality 

consistency.  The  criterion  of  reality  must  lie  in  the  con- 
sequences in  the  way  of  immediate  sense  experience. 
Knowledge  rests,  in  the  last  analysis,  upon  perception. 

For,  with  the  key  furnished  by  Porphyry,  we  can  see 
the  import  of  the  quotations  given  by  Plato  in  the  Theae- 
tetus.  The  homo  mensura  tenet,  which  Plato  quotes, 
means  that  if  facts  make  a  sensible  difference  to  human 
nature,  they  must  be  existent,  and  must  be  what  they  seem 
to  be,  for  the  non-existent  cannot  make  any  difference  to 
human  nature.  And  again  we  read :  "  As  Protagoras 
says  :  '  To  myself  I  am  judge  of  what  is  and  what  is  not 
to  me  '"  —  the  most  unsophisticated  can  trust  his  senses. 
No  need  of  an  Eleatic  to  tell  us.  And  finally :  "  His 
words  are:  'To  whom  a  thing  seems,  that  which  seems 
is'  ";  or,  in  Hegel's  phrase,  "The  essence  must  appear." 
Unless  the  real  can  appear  in  experience  and  be  taken 
at  its  face  value,  not  as  a  lying  universe,  science  is  im- 
possible. And  in  this  appearance,  so  far  as  knowledge  is 
concerned,  human  nature  is  a  necessary  reagent.  Such 
seems  to  me  the  meaning  of  Protagoras.  Such  is  the 
meaning  of  modern  pragmatism. 

Perhaps  the  best  commentary  on  Protagoras  is  his  own 
countryman  and  contemporary,  Empedocles,  who,  with  a 
similar  motive,  was  combating  the  Eleatics  :  "  Go  to  now, 
consider  with  all  thy  powers  in  what  way  each  thing  is 
clear.  Hold  nothing  that  thou  seest  in  greater  credit  than 
what  thou  hearest,  nor  value  thy  resounding  ear  above  the 
clear  instructions  of  thy  tongue ;  and  do  not  withhold  thy 
confidence  in  any  of  the  other  bodily  parts  by  which  there 
is  an  opening  for  understanding,  but  consider  everything 
in  the  way  it  is  clear."  *  Thus  must  we  put  nature  upon 
1  Lines  20-24,  Burnet's  translation. 


From  Protagoras  to   William  James  171 

the  rack.  This  is  Empedocles'  plea  for  sense  evidence ; 
and  his  belief  in  the  dependence  of  this  sense  evidence, 
both  as  to  kind  and  to  range,  upon  the  conditions  of  the 
human  body  —  its  substances  and  pores,  did  not  make  him 
a  subjectivist. 

Plato's  interest,  in  the  Theaetetus,  is  not  in  Protagoras's 
own  meaning,  but  in  the  psychological  and  logical  conse- 
quences which  seem  to  him  to  be  involved  —  quite  unsus- 
pected, as  he  admits,  by  Protagoras  himself  and  his 
disciples.  Thus  Plato  hopes  to  point  a  moral  to  the 
subjectivism  in  his  own  day.  To  make  short  work  of  his 
opponents,  Plato  groups  together  several  doctrines,  the 
homo  mensura  doctrine  of  Protagoras,  the  later  doctrine 
of  Theaetetus  that  knowledge  is  perception  and  the  flux 
theory  of  the  later  Heracliteans,  all  of  which  Plato  gives 
the  brand  of  relativism,  thus  producing  confusion  in  the 
mind  of  his  successors.  And  here,  too,  history  has  repeated 
itself  in  the  hopeless  jungle  of  doctrines  to  which  the  term 
pragmatism  has  been  applied  by  its  critics. 

Plato's  interpretation  of  human  nature,  when  he  sets 
himself  to  "  understand  "  Protagoras,  is  surprisingly  indi- 
vidualistic. "  Man  "  must  mean  "  men."  He  then  pro- 
ceeds to  draw  the  consequences  of  such  an  individualistic 
interpretation.  Protagoras,  like  the  early  Fichte,  had 
failed  to  define  his  ego.  He  had  not  been  forced  like 
Kant,  through  a  long  discussion,  to  have  recourse  to  "  con- 
sciousness in  general."  It  was  simply  natural  for  him, 
coming  before  the  individualistic  period,  and  with  the 
spirit  of  the  natural  scientists  still  upon  him,  to  assume  hu- 
man nature  to  be  one :  or,  as  we  learn  from  the  dialogue 
"  Protagoras,"  to  regard  man  as  primarily  institutional. 

But  man  as  man  does  not  have  perceptions.     So  Plato 


172  Truth  and  Reality 

argils.  Seeming  must  always  be  individual  seeming.  So 
many  men,  so  many  seemings.  If  that  is  the  case,  the 
truth  of  the  seeming  is  not  guaranteed  by  the  individual 
seemings,  whether  of  man  or  of  tadpole,  but  is  the  result 
of  a  constitution  presupposed  in  the  seemings  and  only  to 
be  arrived  at  by  conceptual  construction. 

If  Protagoras  failed  to  define  man,  he  also  failed,  accord- 
ing to  Plato,  to  define  seeming.  Scrutiny  will  show  that 
not  all  immediate  experience  is  to  be  equally  trusted  or  to 
be  regarded  as  equally  valid.  There  are  illusions  of  per- 
ception. Immediate  perception,  therefore,  cannot  be 
trusted  indiscriminately  as  evidence  of  reality.  So  Plato 
makes  the  latter  relativism  do  service  against  the  common- 
sense  theory  of  Protagoras.  But  pathological  cases  should 
not  make  us  discredit  perception  altogether.  In  thinking, 
too,  we  have  error  —  fallacious  and  insane  thinking.  But 
should  we,  therefore,  discredit  all  thinking  ?  Plato  by  his 
brilliant  undiscriminating  criticism  of  perception  paves  the 
way  for  skepticism  altogether.  While  illusions  mean  a 
wrong  assimilation  of  a  present  sense  quality  with  a  com- 
plex of  sense  qualities  as  experienced  in  the  past,  this  does 
not  prove  that  we  have  any  other  way  of  ascertaining  the 
conjunctions  of  qualities  except  by  sense-experience. 
Seeming  must  here  correct  seeming,  through  further  ex- 
perience. Thought  can  only  furnish  a  systematic  method 
of  procedure,  not  the  actual  conjunctions. 

Memory  and  expectancy,  Plato  further  contends,  point 
to  a  constitution  which  cannot  be  expressed  in  terms  of 
immediate  seeming.  In  so  far  as  we  imply  these,  we  have 
transcended  mere  perception.  But  while  this  is  true,  are 
not  memory  and  expectancy  after  all  built  upon  seeming 
— the  re-occurrence  of  an  identical  content  which  suggests 


From  Protagoras  to    William  James  173 

its  own  previous  context?  And  does  not  the  value  of 
memory  lie  in  enabling  us  to  draw  upon  the  conjunctions 
of  past  seemings  in  order  to  meet  future  seemings  ? 

If  you  take  our  feelings  of  value  instead  of  our  percep- 
tions, here  too,  Plato  argues,  we  cannot  speak  of  measure 
or  validity,  so  long  as  we  remain  on  the  plane  of  mere  im- 
mediacy. A  dog-faced  baboon  has  the  same  claim  as  Pro- 
tagoras so  far  as  immediate  feelings  are  concerned.  But  we 
must  not  forget  that  the  r61e  of  thinking  must  He  in  finding 
and  weighing  the  implied  presuppositions  in  our  immediate 
sense  of  values ;  and  that  all  it  can  give  us,  here  too,  is  sys- 
tematic procedure.  It  does  not  create  its  data  in  the  case 
of  value  any  more  than  in  the  case  of  sense  qualities. 

Thus  Plato  argues  in  his  own  matchless  and  one-sided 
way,  that  on  the  plane  of  immediacy  there  can  be  no  ques- 
tion of  truth  or  falsity.  As  seemings  they  equally  exist 
The  problem  of  validity  arises  only  with  conceptual  defi- 
nition, systematic  thinking.  He  must  be  a  wise  man  that 
is  to  be  the  measure.  Truth  cannot  be  decided  on  the 
ground  of  seeming  or  duration,  but  on  the  ground  of  its 
rational  coherency.  If  Plato  shows  at  the  end  of  the 
Theaetetus  that  his  abstract  definition  of  truth  is  circular, 
this  confession  of  logical  failure  is  inevitable,  on  the  intel- 
lectualist  basis,  i.e.,  so  long  as  we  try  to  define  truth  in 
strictly  formal  terms.  The  difficulty  can  only  be  overcome 
when  we  state  truth  pragmatically ;  that  is  to  say,  in  terms 
of  procedure  or  leading. 

The  individualism  which  Plato  falls  into  in  criticizing 
Protagoras  would  make  all  knowledge  impossible.  It  can 
be  turned  against  thought  as  well  as  perception.  Think- 
ing, as  well  as  perception,  must  be  the  reaction  of  indi- 
vidual human  nature.  The  individual  errs  in  inference  as 


1/4  Truth  and  Reality 

well  as  perceptual  judgment.  Individual  thinking  must 
be  corrected,  as  must  illusory  perception,  in  the  course  of 
future  experience,  individual  and  social.  In  our  finite  ex- 
perience, knowledge  is  a  piecemeal  affair,  and  seeming 
must  correct  and  supplement  seeming.  Absolute  truth  is 
for  us  a  limit.  Our  faith  must  be  a  faith  in  the  leading 
of  the  seemings,  even  though  we  never  should  arrive. 
Plato,  in  his  new  enthusiasm,  exaggerated  the  concept, 
as  much  as  Protagoras  exaggerated  perception.  The  con- 
cept is  a  splendid  tool,  but  its  value  lies  in  its  anticipation 
of  reality  as  sensed  and  felt,  as  concrete  and  individual. 
Plato,  the  absolutist,  by  failing  to  recognize  this  fact  plays 
into  the  hands  of  the  skeptic. 

Plato  sometimes  narrowly  escapes  giving  us  the  whole 
truth.  In  the  Symposium  and  Phsedrus  he  arrives  at  the 
concept  of  beauty  by  discovering  the  common  beauty  in 
many  instances,  "  going  from  one  to  two,  and  from  two  to 
all  fair  forms,  and  from  fair  forms  to  fair  actions,  from 
fair  actions  to  fair  notions,  until  from  fair  notions  he  ar- 
rives at  the  notion  of  absolute  beauty,  and  at  last  knows 
what  the  essence  of  beauty  is."  In  other  places  he  em- 
ploys the  method  of  limits;  and  again  that  of  mystical 
appreciation.  But  the  beauties  of  earth,  the  immediate 
facts,  are  only  stepping-stones,  the  first  rungs  of  the  Jacob's 
ladder  which,  once  having  ascended,  the  soul  is  satisfied 
and  does  not  need  to  redescend  to  test  the  concept  with 
reference  to  the  facts.  Even  when  it  is  forced  to  rede- 
scend, as  in  the  case  of  rulers  serving  apprenticeship  in 
the  world  of  shadows,  it  is  only  to  mark  the  deviations 
from  the  Idea,  not  to  verify  it.  At  least  such  seems  Plato's 
attitude  in  the  Republic,  Symposium  and  Phaedo. 

What  misled  Plato,  apart  from  his  poetic  bent  of  mind, 


From  Protagoras  to   William  James  175 

was  his  passionate  interest  in  one  group  of  concepts,  viz., 
the  normative  concepts,  which  he  confused  with  the  class 
concepts,  which  he  also  regarded  as  Ideas.  In  the  case  of 
the  normative  ideals  or  limits,  it  does  seem  as  though  they 
must  be  primarily  a  priori  —  only  elicited  by  the  midwife 
experience.  For  without  our  ideal  demands  or  instincts 
for  meaning  and  beauty,  we  would  not  seek  for  meaning, 
for  unity,  or  for  order  within  the  chaotic  world  of  the  im- 
mediate. This  formal  interest  came  to  dominate  largely 
the  ancient  world  through  the  influence  of  Plato  and  the 
new  ethical  and  religious  spirit  of  the  age. 

In  Protagoras  and  Plato  we  have  the  two  poles  of  the 
problem  of  knowledge.  It  is  the  merit  of  Protagoras  to 
have  shown  that  there  can  be  no  knowledge  without  the 
evidence  of  immediate  experience.  What  seems  must  be, 
or  science  is  impossible.  It  is  the  merit  of  Plato  to  have 
shown  that  there  can  be  no  knowledge  without  system- 
atic thinking.  '"  Without  concepts  sensation  is  blind.  Pro- 
tagoras may  have  over-emphasized  the  place  of  sense  per- 
ception in  investigation.  Plato  slighted  the  perpetual  data 
and  was  inclined  to  let  the  mill  of  reason  grind  in  vacua. 
Each  developed  his  brilliant  half-truth  as  a  corrective  to 
the  prevailing  tendency  of  the  age,  Protagoras  in  oppo- 
sition to  the  apriorism  of  the  Eleatics,  Plato  against  the 
immediatism  of  Aristippus.  If  they  did  not  emphasize  the 
other  side,  it  was  for  the  reason  that  it  is  not  necessary  to 
carry  coals  to  Newcastle.  By  such  zig-zag  the  history  of 
thought  progresses. 

Ill 

It  remained  for  modern  science,  in  its  brilliant  history, 
to  show  the  importance  of  both  hypothesis  and  immediacy. 


176  Truth  and  Reality 

Data  become  science  only  when  illuminated  by  thinking 
or  hypothesis.  Science  is  the  constructive  or  systematic 
functioning  of  human  nature,  not  mere  perceptual  conti- 
nuity with  its  environment.  It  is  the  purpose  of  science 
to  construct  or  build  out,  on  the  basis  of  past  experience, 
a  conceptual  network  or  differentiation  of  purposes  to  meet 
the  variety  of  properties  and  changes  in  the  environment. 
The  equivalents  furnished  by  our  scientific  system  may 
be  artificial  enough,  tools  merely  for  our  anticipation  and 
mastery  of  the  processes,  as  in  the  physical  sciences ;  or 
they  may  be  of  a  piece  with  the  world  with  which  they 
deal,  and  lead  to  understanding  and  appreciation,  as  in 
social  relations;  but  in  any  case  our  ideal  construction 
must  be  verified  with  reference  to  the  ongoing  of  experi- 
ence. 

To  be  sure  this  building  out  of  immediacy  has  been  rec- 
ognized in  natural  science  primarily.  And  here  we  have 
lagged  behind  the  Greeks.  The  immediacy  of  perception, 
bound  up  with  the  specific  energies  of  the  senses,  is  the 
only  immediacy  adequately  taken  account  of  by  modern 
science.  The  other  type  of  immediacy,  that  of  feeling  and 
will-attitudes,  involving  physiologically,  beside  the  specific 
cerebral  tendencies,  the  more  diffuse  changes  of  the  motor, 
sympathetic  and  vascular  systems,  has  been  largely  ig- 
nored. Yet  the  values  of  objects  must  be  regarded  as 
equally  significant  with  their  properties.  If  the  sense  qual- 
ities are  functional  relations  of  human  nature  to  its  ob- 
jects, so  also  are  values.  Objects  no  more  have  qualities 
in  the  abstract  than  values,  and  by  value  I  mean  the  satis- 
faction which  objects  can  furnish  to  our  will  as  contrasted 
with  the  sense  differences  which  they  can  make.  If  the 
world  of  properties  is  capable  of  being  taken  in  an  orderly 


From  Protagoras  to    William  James  177 

way,  so  also  is  the  world  of  values.  And  the  later  Sophists 
were  quite  right  in  saying  that  if  one  is  subjective,  so  is 
the  other.  What  we  must  recognize  is  that  if,  by  means 
of  hypothesis  and  experiment,  we  can  build  out  the  imme- 
diacy of  sense  qualities  into  an  objective  world,  we  can  just 
as  surely  build  out  an  objective  world  of  worth  from  the 
immediacy  of  our  longings  and  demands  with  their  implied 
formal  presuppositions.  The  immediacy  of  feeling,  too, 
has  cognitive  significance  and  can  be  made  to  yield,  with 
freedom  and  intelligence  of  development,  an  objective  order 
of  worth,  as  surely  as  natural  science,  out  of  the  immedi- 
acy of  sense,  can  build  the  order  of  nature.  This  has  been 
and  is  being  done  in  the  esthetic  and  religious  development 
of  the  race.  The  pragmatic  method  applies  to  religion  as 
much  as  to  science ;  and  though  one  life  is  too  short  to 
know  much  either  about  nature  or  the  gods,  the  experience 
of  the  race  must  supplement  and  correct  the  experience  of 
the  individual.  The  solidarity  of  the  race  is  presupposed 
in  either  case. 

We  may  define  pragmatism  as  scientific  method  con- 
scious of  its  own  procedure.  The  scientist  has  not  always 
known  what  he  was  about.  Sometimes  he  has  emphasized 
the  essentially  innate  nature  of  truth  with  Descartes  and 
his  followers.  Sometimes  he  has  demanded  pure  percep- 
tions and  a  tabula  rasa.  Even  when  he  has  furnished  good 
canons  of  procedure,  he  has  not  always  been  awake  to  what 
he  has  been  doing.  Pragmatism  is  not  the  invention  of  a 
new  method ;  it  does  not  furnish  any  new  hypothesis ;  but 
it  insists  that  the  scientific  spirit  of  tentative  hypothesis 
and  verification  shall  dominate  all  our  investigation,  not 
only  naturalistic ,  but  philosophic  as  well.  We  must  shear 
the  luxuriance  of  imagination  to  fit  the  facts.  Life  must 


178  Truth  and  Reality 

be  given  to  winged  thought  by  touching  the  earth  of  evi- 
dence again.  And  unless  the  hypothesis,  however  ingen- 
ious, helps  us  to  anticipate  and  control,  or  understand  and 
appreciate  the  onrushing  stream  of  human  experience,  it 
is  not  science  but  fiction,  no  matter  how  internally  consist- 
ent it  may  be.  The  Newtonian  equations,  the  religious 
beliefs,  must  terminate  in  the  intended  facts.  Failing  this, 
ideal  construction  must  set  to  work  afresh,  until  at  least 
greater  approximation  is  reached.  An  hypothesis,  whether 
of  atoms  or  morals,  God  or  devil,  is  true  because  it  works. 
We  do  not  wonder  over  the  disappointment  at  this  lack 
of  novelty  in  the  pragmatic  method.  No  doubt  Dr.  Paul 
Carus  expresses  a  general  feeling  when  he  says  :  "If  prag- 
matism, as  commonly  understood,  were  truly  nothing  but 
another  name  for  '  scientific  method,'  it  would  not  have 
anything  new  to  offer."1  But  what  the  critic  forgets  is 
that  pragmatism  is  the  baptism  of  a  new  consciousness  as 
to  the  meaning  of  science.  It  makes  definite  and  articulate 
what  was  only  implied  before.  Few  great  reformations 
have  been  original,  to  any  great  extent,  in  their  intellectual 
content.  Their  originality  has  lain  mostly  in  the  simplicity 
and  directness  of  their  aim — the  clearness  and  inten- 
sity of  their  emphasis.  And  there  is  a  good  deal  of  differ- 
ence between  the  common  talk  of  agreement,  begotten 
between  intellectual  sleeping  and  waking,  and  the  clear 
consciousness  of  what  the  agreement  of  an  idea  with  its 
object  means  — the  termination  or  leading  of  an  idea  into 
its  intended  facts.  It  emphasizes  negatively  that  there  is 
no  other  criterion  of  validity  beside  conduct ;  that  mystical 
feeling,  however  subjectively  satisfactory,  must,  in  order  to 
be  proven  true,  submit  to  the  test  of  the  procedure  of  ex- 

1  Monist,  October,  1910,  p.  615. 


From  Protagoras  to    William  James  179 

perience ;  and  that  no  a  priori  conviction,  no  dogmatic 
insistence  upon  the  inconceivability  of  the  contrary,  can 
have  anything  more  than  subjective  significance,  unless 
it  terminates  in  the  systematic  experience  of  the  individual 
and  the  race.  They  are  no  substitutes,  in  any  case,  for 
investigation  and  have,  as  feelings,  attached  to  all  sorts 
of  ideas.  We  have  but  a  single  criterion  of  truth  —  the 
procedure  of  experience. 

Does  truth,  as  thus  conceived,  seem  transient,  provi- 
sional'and  pluralistic  ?  This  is  only  because  we  have  become 
intellectually  honest — conscious  of  our  poverty.  Truth 
has  just  as  much  unity  and  constancy  as  its  use  in  experi- 
ence indicates.  Grand  assumptions  about  it  do  not  in- 
crease either  its  permanency  or  reality.  Its  permanency 
and  adequacy  to  reality  must  be  tested  by  our  ability  to  take 
reality  that  way.  Its  leading,  so  far  as  effective,  is  not 
arbitrary  but  due  to  its  seizing  upon  the  real  characteristics 
of  its  intended  object,  whether  eternal  or  transient. 

If  pragmatism  is  essentially  the  scientific  spirit,  there 
is  always  need  of  a  renaissance  of  the  pragmatic  conscious- 
ness in  science.  The  authority  of  great  names — the 
Archimedeses  and  Aristotles  and  Newtons ;  the  impressive- 
ness  of  tradition  and  technique,  are  too  apt  to  overshadow 
the  real,  inductive  spirit.  We  read  facts  out  of  court,  or 
at  least  refuse  to  investigate,  because  the  facts  or  alleged 
facts  are  supposed  to  be  contrary  to  "  laws,"  the  only  status 
of  which  is  that  of  generalizations  from  facts.  How  great 
a  r61e  the  a  priori  inconceivable,  as  we  are  pleased  to 
call  our  intellectual  prejudices,  still  plays  in  science !  If 
it  is  no  longer  the  inconceivability  of  the  antipodes,  it 
is  the  inconceivability  of  action  at  a  distance,  the  incon- 
ceivability of  mind  influencing  body,  etc.  When  shall  we 


180  Truth  and  Reality 

learn  that  the  best  test  of  whether  a  fact  can  happen  is 
whether  it  does  happen  and  that  it  is  the  province  of  reason 
not  to  prescribe  the  conditions,  but  to  discover  the  condi- 
tions under  which  events  happen?  If  our  intellectual 
models  make  our  procedure  impossible,  we  must  revise  the 
models.  If  this  is  difficult  in  science,  how  much  more  in 
religious  and  legal  practice.  What  a  reform  in  science,  law 
and  religion  alike,  if  we  once  had  the  courage  to  drop  hy- 
potheses which  make  no  difference  to  our  procedure.  The 
value  of  conceptual  technique  is  precisely  to  furnish  such 
leading  as  will  terminate  in  the  facts.  If  it  substitutes  an 
abstract  model  for  the  facts,  it  should  not  be  for  the  sake  of 
hypostatizing  the  model,  but  for  the  sake  of  better  antici- 
pating the  facts. 

IV 

In  its  general  emphasis,  as  well  as  in  its  thesis,  modern 
pragmatism  follows  closely  its  ancient  forbear.  The  scope 
of  hypothesis  or  creative  imagination  has  been  largely  neg- 
lected by  modern  pragmatists,  as  it  was  by  Protagoras  of 
old,  and  for  similar  polemic  reasons.  It  is  obviously  so 
neglected  in  the  thesis  that  truth  consists  in  its  conse- 
quences. It  would  be  at  least  equally  true  to  say  that  truth 
consists  in  hypothesis  or  in  certain  instinctive  demands 
for  unity  and  simplicity,  for  without  either  there  could  be 
no  such  thing  as  truth.  We  should  be  simply  staring  at 
things.  We  must  not  neglect  the  creative  factor  in  knowl- 
edge—  the  building  out  by  constructive  imagination,  as 
prompted  by  certain  fundamental  instincts,  beyond  the  im- 
mediate, beyond  sensations  and  feelings.  It  is  true  that 
this  building  out  must  be  supported  in  the  end  by  evidence, 
by  consequences  of  immediate  experience,  but  it  is  also 


From  Protagoras  to    William  James  1 8 1 

true  that  without  this  building  out  of  creative  imagination, 
we  would  remain  hopelessly  swamped  in  the  slush  of  sub- 
jectivism. On  the  other  hand,  mere  hypothesis,  while  it 
may  have  its  subjective  value,  cannot  by  itself  give  us  ob- 
jective truth.  It  must  be  tested  by  evidence,  as  well  as  by 
the  subjective  satisfaction  which  it  gives.  And  pragmatism 
has  done  well  to  insist  upon  this  truth,  as  against  the  sub- 
jective imagination  of  such  philosophies  as  Hegelianism. 

In  two  important  respects  modern  pragmatism  has  the 
advantage  over  ancient.  One  is  in  its  superior  psycholog- 
ical tools.  It  has  shown  more  clearly  than  before,  espe- 
cially through  William  James,  the  teleological  nature  of 
the  thought  process,  its  connective  value  in  the  flow  of 
experience,  how  ideas  lean  on  facts  and  how  facts  are 
organized  by  means  of  ideas.1  The  other  advantage  of 
modern  pragmatism  is  its  evolutionary  and  racial  con- 
sciousness. To  a  large  extent  it  is  the  outgrowth  of  the 
Darwinian  spirit.  It  is  a  theory  of  the  survival  of  hypoth- 
eses— those  surviving  which  fit  experience.  But  a  theory 
of  elimination,  important  as  it  is,  cannot  by  itself  account 
for  knowledge,  any  more  than  the  doctrine  of  the  survival 
of  the  fittest  can  account  for  life.  The  variations  them- 
selves must  be  understood  through  their  structural  con- 
tinuity with  the  past.  In  the  case  of  knowledge  this 
continuity  becomes  an  instinctive  or  "  physical  heritage  "  in 
the  form  of  certain  demands,  tendencies  or  needs.  And  it 
also  becomes  a  psychological  continuity  or  an  imitative  de- 
pendence upon  the  institutional  life  of  the  race,  the  "  social 
heritage."  The  ideal  variations  or  purposes  must  find  their 
explanation  in  this  twofold  background,  i.e.,  the  biological 

1  In  this  connection  should  also  be  mentioned  the  important  influence  of 
Dewey's  "  Logical  Studies"  and  Schiller's  "  Humanism." 


1 82  Truth  and  Reality 

i 

tendencies  as  becoming  conscious  of  themselves  in  attempt- 
ing to  assimilate  the  social  heritage,  and  use  it  in  the  ser- 
vice of  the  ever  new  problems  of  life.  From  this  process 
emerge  the  new  purposes,  guesses  or  hypotheses.  These 
ideal  constructions  or  demands  must  be  tried  out  with  ref- 
erence to  further  experience ;  and  those  will  survive  which 
afford  an  advantage  in  meeting  the  intended  object.  More 
than  one  hypothesis  may  work  for  the  time  being ;  and  at 
a  certain  stage  of  development  a  cruder  hypothesis  may 
work  better  than  a  conceptually  more  perfect  one.  The 
crude  four  elements  of  Empedocles  seemed  to  work  better 
for  the  time  being  than  the  ingenious  hypothesis  of  Anax- 
agoras  or  even  than  the  atomic  theory  of  Democritus. 
The  axiom  of  an  eye  for  an  eye  and  anthropomorphic  gods 
worked  better  at  a  certain  stage  of  development  than  the 
golden  rule  and  spiritual  theism.  In  the  long  run,  how- 
ever, the  workability  of  an  hypothesis  must  mean  corre- 
spondence with  the  reality  which  it  intends  —  the  seizing 
upon  its  identities  for  the  guidance  of  conduct. 

Beliefs,  instinctive  or  articulate,  are  the  grist  which 
the  pragmatic  mill  must  grind  or  else  grind  itself.  Human 
nature,  conditioned  as  it  is  by  its  biological  and  social  back- 
ground, constructs  its  belief-worlds  to  supplement  its  inner 
needs.  It  is  this  impulse  to  create  belief-worlds  which  has 
made  religion  advance  by  ever  new  variations  and  elimina- 
tions from  fetishism  and  nature-worship  to  ethical  mono- 
theism; which  has  made  science  advance  from  the 
hypothesis  of  Thales  that  all  is  water,  to  our  modern  com- 
plex physical  and  chemical  theories.  These  belief-worlds  are 
not  only  thrown  about  us  by  ourselves,  in  our  individual 
capacity,  to  be  cozy  in  our  world.  They  are  first  of  all 
thrown  about  us  by  the  race  which  wraps  us  snugly  in  the 


From  Protagoras  to   William  James  183 

swaddling  clothes  of  its  own  making.  Else  we  would  all 
start  naked,  to  cover  ourselves  with  fig  leaves.  Every 
scientist  would  be  a  Thales.  It  is  only  in  the  course  of  indi- 
vidual experience,  if  at  all,  that  we  make  the  old  thought- 
clothes  correspond  with  the  new  individual  preferences. 


Knowledge,  we  have  seen,  must  mean  the  differences 
that  stimuli  make  to  reflective  human  nature.  All  ex- 
perience must  be  assessed  from  the  reflective  level  —  must 
issue  in  articulate  judgments,  if  we  are  to  have  truth. 
Perhaps  we  may,  in  the  light  of  the  preceding  discussion, 
venture  to  offer  the  following  tentative  definition  of  truth. 
Truth  consists  in  the  differences  which  objects  make  to  the 
reflective  conduct  of  human  nature,  as  in  its  evolutionary 
process  it  attempts  to  control  and  understand  its  world. 
This  definition  of  truth  recognizes  the  contribution  of  both 
the  empiricists  and  rationalists,  Protagoras  and  Plato. 
Both  hypothesis  and  evidence,  reflection  and  immediacy, 
are  necessary  to  truth.  It  recognizes,  moreover,  the  fini- 
tude  of  truth  as  an  adjustment  to  an  infinite  process. 

Past  misunderstandings,  however,  lead  me  to  think  that 
the  pragmatic  doctrine  of  truth  needs  more  explicit  defini- 
tion at  two  points.  One  has  to  do  with  the  significance 
of  the  term  conduct,  the  other  has  to  do  with  the  relation 
of  pragmatism  to  nominalism. 

First  a  word  as  regards  the  significance  of  the  term 
conduct.  My  own  conception  of  pragmatism  is  that  its 
definition  of  truth  in  terms  of  conduct  is  fundamental.  In , 
this  sense  it  is  a  "practical  "  theory  of  truth.  It  has  to  do 
with  the  procedure  of  thought,  the  control  of  our  ideas  in 
relation  to  an  intended  object.  But  here  there  has  been 


184  Truth  and  Reality 

considerable  confusion.  The  original  use  of  the  term  prag- 
matism by  C.  S.  Peirce  had  to  do  with  laboratory  conduct 
specifically — the  procedure  in  the  experimental  verification 
of  an  hypothesis.  In  James,  Schiller  and  Dewey  the  em- 
phasis has  been  on  biological  conduct  —  the  attainment  of 
certain  goods  on  the  part  of  the  organism.  No  doubt  truth 
is  tested  in  part  by  our  ability  to  control  the  environment 
for  our  specific  purposes.  But  truth  need  not  be  practical 
or  instrumental  in  this  external  sense.  Its  leading  may 
be  of  a  formal  kind,  as  in  mathematical  procedure.  Its 
aim,  too,  may  be  that  of  understanding  and  sympathy, 
rather  than  use,  as  in  our  striving  to  know  other  egos.  I 
have  used  conduct  in  a  wider  sense  —  including  the  con- 
duct of  the  understanding  as  well  as  biological  conduct.1 
Truth  must  be  measured  in  terms  of  the  reflective  proce- 
dure of  our  entire  human  nature  in  realizing  its  tendencies, 
formal  or  practical.  It  still  remains  true,  on  this  more  in- 
clusive definition,  that  the  truth  of  an  idea  consists  in  its 
leading,  its  ability  to  guide  in  the  direction  of  its  intended 
object,  whether  a  chemical  compound  or  an  algebraic  root. 
Thus  taken,  the  term  pragmatism  will  be  true  both  to  its 
Greek  derivation  and  to  all  the  requirements  of  logic.  The 
rules  which  the  will  must  acknowledge  as  governing  this 
procedure  of  truth,  I  have  discussed  elsewhere.2 

As  regards  the  relation  of  pragmatism  to  nominalism, 
there  has  been  considerable  wobbling  between  the  definition 
of  truth  in  terms  of  leading  on  the  one  hand,  and  in  terms 
of  particulars  on  the  other.  I  believe  these  to  be  incom- 
patible definitions.  If  truth  consists  in  the  sum  of  par- 
ticulars, there  can  be  no  leading.  A  photographic  or 

1  See  chapter  X,  pp.  187-189. 

2  See  chapters  VII  and  VIII. 


From  Protagoras  to   William  James  185 

cinematographic  copy  would  be  quite  useless  for  purposes 
of  conduct.  Truth  can  never  lie  in  the  sum  of  particulars 
or  their  mere  external  association.  Who  wants  to  count  the 
sand  on  the  seashore  or  the  leaves  of  the  trees  ?  It  would 
be  quite  worthless,  even  if  not  practically  impossible.  The 
leading  is  made  possible  by  the  thread  of  identity  —  the 
ability  to  substitute  certain  constant  characteristics  for  the 
motley  world  of  facts  and  changes  and  thus  to  manipulate 
it  in  the  service  of  our  purposes.  In  the  Litany  of  prag- 
matism let  it  be  written  :  From  the  taint  of  mediaeval  nom- 
inalism, deliver  us.1  With  such  an  understanding  as  re- 
gards the  meaning  of  pragmatism,  it  ought  to  proceed  more 
efficiently  on  its  career  of  simplifying  and  unlocking  the 
problems  of  life,  theoretical  and  practical. 

1  In  this  I  am  happy  to  find  myself  in  agreement  with  my  friend,  Dr. 
Horace  Meyer  Kallen.  See  Jour.  Phil.  Psych,  and  Sci.  Meth.,  "The  Affilia- 
tions of  Pragmatism,"  Vol.  VI,  pp.  657  and  658. 


CHAPTER  X 
WHAT  PRAGMATISM  is  AND  is  NOT 

THE  confusion  in  regard  to  pragmatism  by  its  critics  on 
the  one  hand  and  the  variety  of  doctrines  included  under 
that  term  by  its  defenders  on  the  other  hand,  make  it  highly 
desirable  for  all  concerned  that  there  should  be  a  definite 
understanding  as  to  what  pragmatism  means.  Failing  such 
an  understanding,  the  term  pragmatism  should  be  dropped 
out  of  the  vocabulary  of  philosophy.  This  would  be  a  pity, 
as  the  term  short-hands  a  good  deal  of  circumlocution  arid 
has  already  been  widely  used.  What  place  pragmatism 
shall  ultimately  come  to  have  as  regards  various  schools  of 
epistemology  or  metaphysics,  whether  the  old  labels  of 
idealist  and  realist,  spiritualist  and  materialist,  empiricist 
and  apriorist,  can  still  be  retained,  is  of  little  consequence 
except  to  those  who  must  set  their  house  in  order,  provid- 
ing that  pragmatism  as  a  doctrine  must  be  reckoned  with. 

In  the  first  place,  pragmatism  as  a  doctrine  is  so  simple 
and  so  old  as  a  matter  of  scientific  procedure  that  it  is  im- 
possible to  understand  why  so  much  dust  should  have  been 
raised  about  it  by  its  opponents.  It  is  simply  the  applica- 
tion of  the  ordinary  method  of  the  scientific  testing  of 
an  hypothesis  to  philosophic  hypotheses  as  well.  It  is 
certainly  high  time  that  philosophy,  in  many  respects  the 
oldest  of  the  sciences,  should  take  on  scientific  definite- 
ness  and  severity  or  else  regard  itself  as  a  department  of 
poetry. 

1 86 


WJiat  Pragmatism  is  and  is  Not  187 

Now  pragmatism,  as  so  often  stated,  holds  that  you  can- 
not test  the  truth  of  an  hypothesis  or  judgment  indepen- 
dent of  conduct.  The  truth  of  an  idea  or  plan  must  be 
tested  by  the  procedure  to  which  it  leads.  You  can,  of 
course,  insist  with  the  mediaeval  critics  of  astronomy  that 
there  must  be  seven  planets  because  there  are  seven  days 
in  the  week,  etc.,  i.e.,  from  the  a  priori  fitness  of  things, 
but  the  curiosity  upon  which  science  is  based  always  insists 
on  trying  the  assumption ;  and  if  experience  indicates  more 
planers,  we  revise  the  hypothesis  to  fit  the  facts.  This  is 
the  "  practical "  testing  of  a  doctrine  in  science. 

The  testing  of  a  doctrine  in  terms  of  conduct,  or  compar- 
ing the  anticipated  consequences  with  the  consequences  to 
which  it  leads  in  being  carried  out,  need  not  always  mean 
material  consequences.  There  is  a  conduct  of  the  under- 
standing as  well  as  a  conduct  involving  certain  perceptual 
events  as  its  outcome.  The  procedure  may  be  entirely  of 
a  logical  kind  as  in  formal  logic  and  pure  mathematics. 
But  here,  too,  the  idea  is  true  only  as  it  terminates  con- 
sistently in  its  intended  result.  The  consequences  must  be 
shown  to  follow  from  the  definitions  and  not  from  assump- 
tions or  intuitions  surreptitiously  introduced  in  the  course 
of  the  argument.  The  rules  of  logic,  as  the  rules  of  ethics, 
have  been  adopted  for  their  convenience  in  conduct. 

Common  sense  and  intuition  may  short-hand  our  scien- 
tific methods,  and  are  valuable  in  many  cases,  but  they  are 
not  truth,  in  the  scientific  sense,  until  the  conclusions  thus 
arrived  at  are  systematically  tested  in  the  actual  procedure 
of  experience. 

We  sometimes  have  to  choose  between  different  rules  or 
concepts.  In  this  case  we  must  ask  ourselves  what  dif- 
ference will  it  make  if  I  choose  one  rather  than  another 


1 88  Truth  and  Reality 

method  of  procedure.  It  may  make  no  ultimate  difference. 
The  same  problem  can  be  solved  by  plain  arithmetic  or  by 
algebra.  Both  solutions  are  equally  true.  Only  habit  and 
convenience,  therefore,  can  decide  between  them.  When 
two  roads  lead  to  the  place  to  which  I  want  to  go,  other 
things  being  equal,  I  take  the  most  economic  road.  Es- 
thetic or  other  motives,  however,  may  influence  me,  be- 
sides the  mere  desire  of  arriving,  and  so  I  may  choose  the 
longest  route.  And  so  in  the  choice  of  hypotheses.  But 
in  any  case  the  hypothesis  is  verified  only  as  it  terminates 
in  the  intended  result ;  as  its  ideal  consequences  tally  with 
the  conditions  which  I  have  set  myself  to  meet,  whether 
purely  logical  or  perceptual  as  well. 

Now  I  certainly  have  a  right  to  profit  by  previous  expe- 
rience, whether  my  own  or  that  of  others.  I  may  have 
faith  in  a  chart  of  the  road  already  provided,  without  go- 
ing through  the  trouble  of  mapping  the  routes  in  that  par- 
ticular neighborhood  again.  But  this  deductive  truth  rests 
no  less  on  conduct ;  and  if  it  should  fail,  in  the  process  of 
adjustment,  to  satisfy  the  demands  of  further  conduct  or 
experience,  it  must  be  revised,  however  venerable  or  dis- 
tinguished may  be  its  ancestry.  Truth  about  reality  as  a 
whole,  or  any  part  of  it,  however  abstract,  consists  in  the 
differences  that  reality  makes  to  our  reflective  purposes  in 
their  historic  realization. 

To  ask,  therefore,  whether  a  statement  is  true  is  equiva- 
lent to  asking:  What  must  we  take  the  selected  object  as, 
in  the  procedure  of  experience  ?  This  is  as  true  of  the 
formula,  2  +  2  =  4,  as  of  the  proposition,  Socrates  is  mor- 
tal. For  some  purposes  taking  two  pounds  twice  is  equiv- 
alent to  taking  four  pounds  once.  This  obviously  is  not 
always  so.  Taking  two  women  one  hundred  pounds  each 


What  Pragmatism  is  and  is  Not  189 

is  not  equivalent  to  taking  one  woman  two  hundred  pounds 
if  the  purpose  be  marriage.  In  the  former  case  you 
will  be  thrown  into  jail  for  bigamy.  The  intuitional 
character  of  the  formula  is  due  to  the  fact  that  we  have 
forgotten  the  concrete  procedure,  the  beads,  for  example, 
that  were  used  by  the  primary  teacher  to  overcome  our 
stolid  incredulity.  The  only  way  that  you  can  know  that 
you  know  is  by  trying  out  your  knowledge,  and  even  then, 
owing  to  the  finitude  of  our  nature  and  the  complexity  of 
reality,  our  certainty  is  decidedly  empirical.  We  no  doubt 
confront  the  environment  with  all  sorts  of  tendencies  or 
categories,  more  numerous  than  Kant's  table,  but  truth 
they  are  not,  until  they  are  reflectively  tried  out,  in  the 
procedure  of  experience. 

But  is  not  truth  agreement  with  reality  ?  the  hard-headed 
critic  always  comes  back.  Yes,  certainly,  i.e.,  with  the  re- 
ality which  we  intend,  which  may  be  the  constitution  of 
number  or  of  a  chemical  compound.  We  rarely  ever  aim 
at  reality  as  a  whole,  any  more  than  we  aim  at  a  bear  as  a 
whole  when  shooting  at  him.  The  subject  of  our  judg- 
ments is  almost  always  a  selected  part  of  reality,  not  real- 
ity in  general.  But  the  pragmatist  doctrine,  so  far  from 
denying  that  truth  is  agreement  with  its  intended  reality, 
has  for  its  purpose  to  make  explicit  what  we  mean  by 
such  agreement.  And  what  we  mean  is  what  science 
always  has  insisted,  viz.,  that  the  consequences  which 
follow  from  the  hypothesis,  or  the  constitution  of  the 
object  as  we  have  conceived  it  on  the  basis  of  past  ex- 
perience, shall  tally  with  the  consequences  in  dealing  with 
the  object,  or  with  further  experience,  formal  or  empirical, 
according  to  the  problem  set.  There  is  no  such  thing  as 
agreement  in  the  abstract ;  no  way  of  finding  out  the  truth 


icjo  Truth  and  Reality 

of  an  idea  by  merely  examining  its  eternal  fitness  in  gen- 
eral. It  must,  in  order  to  be  true,  fit  its  intended  consti- 
tution, as  Royce  has  so  splendidly  shown,  and  this  can 
only  be  found  out  by  observing  the  results  of  our  experi- 
ment, by  the  tallying  of  our  hypothesis  with  our  syste- 
matic observations.  The  data  thus  caught,  simplified  and 
organized  through  the  network  of  our  concepts,  which  in 
turn  have  been  progressively  modified  to  meet  the  demands 
of  the  data,  is  what  we  mean  by  the  laws  of  science. 
Whatever  reality  may  be,  science  is  a  systematic  sorting 
of  experience  in  the  realization  of  our  interests. 

I  suspect,  however,  that  what  has  given  rise  to  this  long 
and  confused  controversy  is  not  pragmatism  as  an  episte- 
mological  theory,  but  the  various  epistemological  and  meta- 
physical consequences  which  some  of  the  "  pragmatists  " 
have  arrived  at,  supposedly  by  the  pragmatic  criterion,  and 
which  have  been  included  by  them  and  their  critics  under 
the  general  heading  of  pragmatism.  Of  course,  if  you 
include  any  professed  pragmatist's  results  under  prag- 
matism, then  you  will  have  an  indefinite  number  of 
pragmatisms  with  hopeless  confusion  of  the  epistemo- 
logical issue.1  Just  because  a  professed  pragmatist,  even 
William  James,  happens  to  hold  a  doctrine  does  not  neces- 
sarily make  it  part  of  the  theory  of  pragmatism.  His 
philosophic  results  would  have  to  be  tested  by  the  prag- 
matic criterion,  quite  irrespective  of  his  having  subscribed 
to  it.  Even  the  best  people's  conduct  does  not  always 
agree  with  their  ideals.  And  the  pragmatic  criterion  is  an 

1  Lovejoy's  "  Thirteen  Pragmatisms  "  seem  a  petty  allowance,  when  you  con- 
sider the  variety  of  human  nature  and  the  number  of  possible  applications  of 
the  pragmatic  method.  But  such  analysis  has  been  wholesome  in  exposing  the 
confusions  in  the  pragmatist  camp  and  thus  clarifying  the  main  issue.  See 
Jour.  Phil.  Psych,  and  Sci.  Metk.,  Vol.  V,  Nos.  I  and  2. 


What  Pragmatism  is  and  is  Not  191 

epistemological  ideal,  which  we  finites  can,  only  by  cumu- 
lative striving,  if  ultimately,  realize. 

Let  us  see  briefly  now  what  pragmatism  is  not.  In  the 
first  place  pragmatism  does  not  involve  that  the^  true  and 
the  useful  always  coincide.  Such  an  a  priori  assumption 
about  the  universe  is  anything  but  pragmatic.  Truth  may, 
of  course,  turn  out  to  be  useful.  I  would  not  say  with  a 
German  scientist  that  the  best  part  of  science  is  dass  es  gar 
nieht  anwendbar  ist.  The  utilitarian  motive  has  often 
been  important  in  the  investigation  of  truth,  sometimes  on 
the  part  of  the  investigators,  but  more  often  in  the  material 
promotion  of  investigation.  It  is  true,  however,  that  the 
most  important  investigations  in  pure  science,  such  as  the 
beautiful  researches  in  light  and  electricity,  were  carried 
on  without  reference  to  their  utilitarian  consequences  by 
people  inspired  by  a  divine  madness  to  discover  the  hidden 
harmony  of  things  ;  and  their  results  were  finally  patented 
by  people  who  reaped  where  they  had  not  sown.  But 
whether  researches  are  useful  or  not,  their  usefulness  does 
not  make  them  true.  On  the  whole  we  are  doubtless  bet- 
ter able  to  adjust  ourselves  to  an  environment  because  we 
know  more  about  it,  can  respond  to  its  characteristics, 
though  in  limited,  pathological  cases  ignorance  and  decep- 
tion may  be  more  useful  than  truth.  But  the  statement 
that  truth  is,  on  the  whole,  useful  is  a  conclusion  and  not 
a  part  of  pragmatism  as  an  epistemological  criterion. 
Whether  it  is  a  legitimate  pragmatic  result,  any  one  is  free 
to  test,  where  all  hypotheses  must  be  tested,  in  the  proce- 
dure of  experience. 

In  the  second  place,  pragmatism  is  not  equivalent  to  hu- 
manism. No  doubt  it  is  true,  so  far  as  we  are  concerned, 
that  reality  must  pass  through  human  nature  to  be  known. 


1 92  Truth  and  Reality 

We  humans  know  reality  by  the  differences  it  makes  to 
our  human,  specific,  reflective  purposes  in  their  attempt  at 
realization.  But  it  is  not  our  being  human  that  makes  our 
hypotheses  come  true ;  it  is  their  tallying  with  the  consti- 
tution of  the  object  aimed  at,  as  it  appears  in  further 
experience.  And  there  is  nothing  to  show  that  this  ex- 
perience, whether  on  its  logical  or  perceptual  side,  is  pe- 
culiarly human.  The  weight,  or  color,  or  size  or  position 
of  a  thing  is  not  peculiarly  human  as  distinct  from  other 
animals.  A  "dog-faced  baboon,"  so  far  as  we  know,  has 
the  same  sort  of  perceptions  that  we  have,  and  is  subject  to 
the  same  laws  of  association.  If  a  dog-faced  baboon  or  a 
tadpole  should  construct  hypotheses  or  their  equivalents, 
they  would  have  to  be  verified  in  the  same  pragmatic  way  as 
human  hypotheses  are.  It  matters  not  what  sort  of  finite  be- 
ing tries  to  arrive  at  truth,  whether  man,  baboon,  or  angel, 
the  test  of  truth,  so  far  as  we  can  see,  would  be  the  same. 
If  what  is  intended  is  the  statement  that  the  nature  of 
reality  is  made  over  in  knowing  it  and  that  therefore  we 
are  limited  to  the  charmed  circle  of  experience,  this,  too,  is 
an  unpragmatic  assumption.  While  it  is  a  mere  circle  to 
say  that  we  can  know  reality  only  as  it  appears  in  cogni- 
tive experience,  or  for  what  it  must  be  taken  as,  it  is  a 
gratuitous  assumption  to  insist  that  what  reality  is  known- 
as,  is  contrary  to  what  reality  is,  that  the  weights  and 
distances  and  masses  of  things  exist  only  as  we  humans 
take  account  of  them.  When  we  take  account  of  them, 
they  have  meaning  for  us,  but  our  taking  account  of  the 
qualities  of  things  at  all  is  generally  forced  upon  us  by 
their  existence,  which  we  must  meet  in  order  properly  to 
adjust  ourselves.  At  least  it  is  not  pragmatism  to  decide 
a  priori  that  things  are  not  what  they  seem. 


What  Pragmatism  is  and  is  Not  193 

May  there  not  be  cognitive  beings  superior  to  us  hu- 
mans? Or  are  the  humanists  absolutely  convinced  that 
we  humans  are  the  only  cognitive  beings  in  the  universe? 
That  certainly  is  no  part  of  the  pragmatic  theory  of  truth; 
but,  even  if  true,  it  is  not  being  human  that  makes  a  propo- 
sition true,  but  its  termination  in  the  intended  facts. 

Is  pragmatism,  as  a  theory  of  truth,  committed  to  the 
instrumental  point  of  view  as  regards  concepts  ?  Not  in 
the  sense  that  truth  exists  solely  for  the  sake  of  satisfying 
certain  demands  extraneous  to  itself,  for  example  the  bi- 
ological end  of  adjustment.  Truth  sometimes  finds  its 
inspiration  in  such  practical  demands,  but  it  sometimes 
finds  its  motive  in  scientific  curiosity.  In  any  case  the 
test  must  be  the  same.  Truth  is  always  teleological,  be- 
cause it  exists  for  the  sake  of  a  relation  to  a  larger  whole, 
but  this  relation  need  not  be  instrumental  in  the  narrow 
sense  that  truth  is  an  extraneous  tool,  like  a  knife,  to  be 
judged  by  its  mere  success.  False  ideas  may  be  tempora- 
rily successful.  Truth  as  a  matter  of  fact  must  always  be 
imitative  of  its  object  to  a  certain  extent.  It  can  never  be 
conventional  in  its  content,  however  conventional  our  sym- 
bols may  be.  In  the  case  of  knowing  a  system  of  truth  it 
must  be  imitative  of  the  meaning  of  the  object;  in  the  case 
of  thing-objects  it  must  be  imitative  of  certain  qualities  of 
the  object.  Inasmuch  as  our  finite  truth  is  not  exhaustive, 
but  always  implies  a  more,  a  larger  constitution  to  be  in- 
vestigated, it  must  be  regarded,  in  so  far,  as  instrumental 
to  its  own  completion,  a  means  to  its  own  more  compre- 
hensive end. 

Can  the  pragmatic  criterion  be  stated  in  terms  of  sat- 
isfaction ?  That  depends  upon  what  sort  of  satisfaction 
we  mean.  No  doubt  the  seeking  for  truth  has  its  own 


194  Truth  and  Reality 

hedonic  tone,  according  to  its  success  or  failure.  The  sat- 
isfaction, so  far  as  the  truth  interest  is  concerned,  is  the 
tone  accompanying  the  testing  of  the  hypothesis  in  pro- 
cedure, so  far  as  that  special  intent  is  concerned.  But  the 
truth  satisfaction  may  run  counter  to  any  moral  or  es- 
thetic satisfaction  in  the  particular  case.  It  may  con- 
sist in  the  discovery  that  the  friend  we  had  backed 
has  involved  us  in  financial  failure,  that  the  picture  we 
had  bought  from  the  catalogue  description  is  anything  but 
beautiful.  But  we  are  no  longer  uncertain  as  regards  the 
truth.  Our  restlessness,  so  far  as  that  particular  curiosity 
is  concerned,  has  come  to  an  end.  And  this  satisfaction 
may  sometimes  be  strong,  even  when  the  practical  out- 
,  come  is  against  us.  The  rejected  lover  gets  some  peace 
of  mind  from  knowing  the  truth  as  to  his  failure.  But 
this  is  hardly  the  satisfaction  of  winning  his  suit. 

Is  pragmatism  realistic?  Only  so  far  as  it  intends  a 
world  beyond  our  finite  cognitive  purposes.  The  finite 
fragmentary  intent  must  find  its  reality  or  correction  in  a 
larger  whole.  I  do  not  know  of  any  striving  for  truth 
which  is  not  realistic  in  this  sense.  How  could  it  be  a 
striving  for  truth  otherwise  ?  But  obviously  a  criterion  of 
truth  must  be  unbiased  at  the  outset  as  regards  the  episte- 
mological  or  metaphysical  result  of  its  application.  The 
reality  we  seek  to  know  may  ultimately  be  more  expe- 
rience —  yes,  we  must  be  willing  to  have  it  turn  out  to  be 
an  absolute  unity  of  thought,  if  the  procedure  of  truth 
leads  that  way.  But  pragmatism  neither  assumes  at  the 
outset  that  the  object  in  order  to  make  any  difference  to 
the  cognitive  purpose  must  itself  be  experience,  nor  does 
it  assume  a  priori  that  reality  cannot  possibly  be  what  it  is 
known  as  being,  because  external  to  experience.  What 


What  Pragmatism  is  and  is  Not  195 

reality  is,  what  differences  it  can  make,  is  precisely  to  be 
found  out.  The  constitution  of  the  universe  is  idealistic 
or  materialistic,  monistic  or  pluralistic,  according  as  we 
must  take  it,  as  the  outcome  of  the  pragmatic  test.  But 
we  must  all  start  with  the  same  criterion,  else  there  can 
be  no  discussion  of  truth. 

Truth  is  systematic  meaning,  systematic  experience 
about  the  object.  This  meaning,  in  case  we  are  striving 
to  know  other  experience,  must  be  identical  with  the  con- 
tent of  the  object;  but  the  qualities  of  an  object  which  is 
not  experience  may  become  content  for  us  through  per- 
ception. In  any  case  truth  is  our  systematic  percipi,  as  it 
is  revealed  in  our  specific  procedure,  whatever  the  meta- 
physical character  of  the  object  may  turn  out  to  be.  We 
have  no  right  to  take  for  granted  that  what  is  to  be  known 
is  more  content,  independent  of  our  knowing,  with  which  our 
preformed  guess  can  be  accidentally  identical  and  so  be 
called  true  in  advance  of  verification. 

It  is  difficult  for  me  to  understand  what  is  meant  by  un- 
verified truths  —  unverified  science,  truths  which  no  one 
knows  to  be  true,  for  if  anyone  knows  them  to  be  true — God, 
or  man,  or  monkey,  they  have  fulfilled  the  pragmatic  test. 
They  are  seen  to  terminate  or  find  their  completion  in  the 
intended  object.  If  a  proposition  has  no  systematic  basis 
in  experience,  we  speak  of  it  as  a  mere  guess.  As  that 
brilliant  pragmatist,  Xenophanes,  puts  it,  "All  are  free  to 
guess  "  and,  "  These  are  guesses  something  like  the  truth, 
.  .  .  but  by  seeking  they  gradually  find  out  what  is  better." 
In  Xenophanes's  time  there  was  but  little  cumulated  scien- 
tific observation.  Hence  he  is  naturally  impressed  with  the 
guess  character  of  his  statements  about  the  universe. 
When  a  supposition  is  based  upon  analogy  and  previous 


196  Truth  and  Reality 

scientific  observation,  we  call  it  an  hypothesis,  but  it  is  only 
as  the  hypothesis  is  fully  tested  in  terms  of  the  intended 
facts  that  we  call  it  truth.  Truth,  therefore,  so  far  as  we 
finite  seekers  are  concerned,  is  a  limit  which  we  are  far 
from  having  realized.  Whether  we  can  realize  it  or  not, 
only  the  historical  outcome  of  the  pragmatic  test  can  prove. 
It  is  certainly  unpragmatic  to  say  in  advance  that  truth  is 
unrealizable.  In  the  meantime  we  have  our  provisional 
"  truths." 

I  suppose  the  reason  that  some  have  insisted  upon  prop- 
ositions being  true  in  advance  of  being  tested  is  that  in 
individual  experience,  especially  in  an  advanced  stage  of 
science,  we  find  a  large  body  of  social  truths,  which  we  can 
take,  for  practical  purposes,  as  ready-made.  We  find  that 
truths  exist  independent  of  our  individual  verification,  and 
then  some  assume  that  they  exist  independent  of  all  verifica- 
tion. Seeing  the  agreement  of  the  hypothesis  of  gravitation 
with  its  intended  facts,  they  insist  that  the  hypothesis  must 
be  true  in  advance  of  the  discovered  agreement,  as  though 
truth  could  be  a  guess  in  vacuo.  What  they  mean  is 
that  reality  has  a  constitution  in  advance  of  our  investiga- 
tions and  that  so  far  as  our  cognitive  nature  is  concerned 
the  qualities  of  reality  are  not  created,  but  discovered. 
Whether  they  are  created  through  our  volitional  nature,  or 
exist  independent  of  our  act  or  positing,  is  a  question  which 
the  application  of  the  pragmatic  method  alone  can  deter- 
mine. But  all  this  controversy  about  preexisting  truths  is 
a  lexicographical  one  and  would  be  over  if  we  recognized 
the  established  philosophic  usage,  as  old  as  Xenophanes, 
that  truth  is  systematic  meaning,  corrected  and  completed  in 
its  intended  reality. 

If  we  state  truth  thus,  there  can  be  no  ultimate  differ- 


What  Pragmatism  is  and  is  Not  197 

ence  between  truth  and  the  test  of  truth.  A  proposition  is 
proven  to  be  true  because  it  terminates  in  its  intended  ob- 
ject, imitates  this  either  as  regards  its  inner  content  or  as 
regards  its  qualities.  But  it  is  true  for  the  same  reason. 
What  makes  the  test  of  truth  seem  something  different  from 
the  truth  itself  is  that  in  the  process  of  verification  the  test 
seems  external  to  the  intent  of  thought.  It  seems  to  hap- 
pen to  the  idea  in  a  more  or  less  accidental  way.  But  this 
is  a  superficial  way  of  looking  at  the  process  of  discovery. 
For  the  facts  only  happen  to  the  intent  of  thought  because 
we  are  seeking  them,  however  much  our  meaning  may  have 
to  be  corrected  in  the  process.  The  test  is  our  further  ex- 
perience about  the  object  as  selected  by  the  intent.  But 
the  intent  is  not,  taken  by  itself,  the  truth,  any  more  than 
the  consequences  of  further  experience  are  the  truth  taken 
as  external  happenings.  It  is  the  intent  as  terminating  in 
the  selected  facts  which  constitutes  the  truth.  And  this 
termination  is  the  test  of  truth,  or  the  intent  as  tested  con- 
stitutes the  truth. 

Is  pragmatism  a  theory  of  empiricism  as  opposed  to  ra- 
tionalism and  a  priorism  f  No,  pragmatism  is  not  com- 
mitted to  any  a  priori  doctrine  of  the  origin  of  ideas  or 
their  connection.  It  is  not  committed  to  Hume's  associa- 
tion theory  any  more  than  to  Plato's  doctrine  of  recollection 
from  previous  existence.  Pragmatism  may  be  said  to  agree 
with  rationalism  in  holding  that  truth  has  a  formal  side. 
An  hypothesis  or  system  must  be  internally  consistent. 
But  pragmatism  insists  that  this  is  not  sufficient :  there 
must  also  be  external  agreement,  or  agreement  of  the  hy- 
pothesis with  its  intended  facts.  As  regards  the  other 
historic  antithesis,  that  of  empiricism  and  a  priorism,  prag- 
matism is  equally  non-committal  It  is  a  theory  of  the  test 


198  Truth  and  Reality 

of  truth,  not  of  the  origin  of  its  categories  or  postulates. 
Whatever  demands  or  tendencies  are  inherited,  they  must  be 
consciously  tried  out  in  experience  as  regards  their  agree- 
ment with  reality  before  they  can  be  called  true.  The 
categories  might  originate  by  use-inheritance,  by  natural 
selection,  by  divine  implanting,  or  by  mystical  intuition,  so 
far  as  pragmatism  as  a  theory  of  truth  is  concerned.  The 
question  is  :  Will  they  work  in  simplifying  experience  and 
meeting  the  character  of  the  environment?  The  theory 
of  their  origin  must  itself  be  subjected  to  the  pragmatic 
test. 

Is  pragmatism  at  the  outset  committed  to  time  and 
chance  as  the  ultimate  character  of  reality  and,  therefore, 
to  the  impossibility  of  any  final  truth  ?  This  again  is  a 
theory  to  be  tested  by  its  pragmatic  outcome.  A  priori, 
eternalism  may  be  the  outcome  of  pragmatism  as  well  as 
dynamism ;  or  perhaps  partly  the  one,  partly  the  other. 
Because  the  discovery  of  truth  is  a  temporal  process,  it 
does  not  follow  that  truth  relations  as  discovered  are  tem- 
poral. The  truth  2  +  2=4  may  De  eternal,  however  long 
was  the  evolution  which  led  to  its  discovery.  At  any  rate, 
there  can  be  no  such  thing  as  pragmatic  dogmatism. 

A  professed  pragmatist  may  of  course  hold  any  of  these 
doctrines,  and  a  large  number  of  them,  either  as  his  individ- 
ual application  of  the  pragmatic  test  or  for  other  reasons. 
He  may  also,  like  myself,  be  an  Episcopalian,  a  free-trader, 
etc.  Do  all  the  doctrines  and  practices  of  the  Episcopal 
church  become  pragmatisms  when  a  pragmatist  belongs  ? 
I  have  known  pragmatists  to  drink  beer,  to  attend  dime 
theatres,  and  even  to  swear.  Are  all  such  practices  with 
their  implied  damnable  theories  of  life  therefore  pragma- 
tisms ?  And  do  they  also  come  under  Scepticismus,  as  the 


What  Pragmatism  is  and  is  Not  199 

German  critics  would  say  ?  God  forbid.  It  makes  one's 
flesh  fairly  creep  to  think  of  all  these  uncanny  associations 
—  these  sins  on  the  part  of  our  clever  young  critics,  com- 
mitted in  the  name  of  pragmatism.  But  are  they  not, 
after  all,  primarily  sins  against  formal  logic  ?  A  is  a  free- 
trader. A  is  a  pragmatist.  Therefore  all  pragmatists  are 
free-traders.  That  looks  very  much  like  an  illicit  minor 
in  the  third  figure.  It  might  also  be  treated  as  a  fallacy 
of  composition.  It  would  seem  as  though  the  "  intellec- 
tualists  "  ought  to  have  a  little  respect  for  formal  logic. 

If  you  say  that  in  the  above  case  pragmatism  is  not  new 
at  all,  but  as  old  as  science,  I  would  quite  agree  with  you. 
No  one  more  than  the  pragmatist  has  disavowed  any  in- 
tention at  originality.  It  is  better  to  be  true  than  original. 
But  the  amount  of  dust  raised  seems  to  indicate  that  an 
old,  implicit  scientific  procedure  was  but  vaguely  under- 
stood. If  the  result  of  this  paper  should  be  to  convince 
my  readers  that  they  are  all  "  pragmatists,"  then  we  shall 
have  "  peace  on  earth,  good  will  to  men  "  once  more,  than 
which  no  more  blissful  consummation  could  be  desired,  un- 
less it  be  strife. 


CHAPTER  XI 

MEANING  AND  VALIDITY 

IN  dealing  with  truth  we  are  concerned,  not  with  the 
imagery  of  the  thought  process,  but  with  the  consciousness 
of  intent  or  direction.  This  is  the  essential  aspect  of  the 
meaning,  the  imagery  is  a  means  or  by-play.  This  sense 
of  intent  or  direction  is  a  unique  content,  not  analyzable 
into  mere  images  and  their  elements.  If  so,  the  meaning 
would  be  a  subjective  compound,  as  associationism  has 
always  maintained.  The  image,  whether  concrete  or  verbal, 
is  a  way  of  fixating  or  making  definite  the  otherwise  vague 
intent.  How  far  imagery  is  indispensable  to  the  meaning 
process  is  a  matter  for  psychological  analysis  to  determine. 
The  focus  of  attention  may  be  alternately  now  upon  the 
intent  and  now  upon  the  imagery  in  varying  degrees ;  and 
in  some  of  the  transitive  flights  of  the  process  we  may  be 
so  absorbed  in  the  intent  as  to  be  oblivious  of  the  imagery, 
while  in  other  cases  the  focus  may  be  just  as  surely  some 
substantive  bit  of  imagery  which  symbolizes  the  meaning. 
Psychology  so  far  has  emphasized  the  latter  cases. 

The  relevancy  of  the  imagery  to  the  intent  obviously 
varies  with  the  degree  the  meaning  is  concrete  or  abstract. 
In  the  concept  of  humanity,  color  distinctions  cannot  be 
irrelevant.  They  are  part  of  the  concrete  meaning.  The 
meaning  of  a  melody  can  be  a  true  meaning  only  when  it 
reproduces  the  melody,  while  Kepler's  squares  and  New- 

200 


Meaning  and  Validity  20 1 

ton's  equations  must  be  regarded  merely  as  artificial  tools 
for  fixating  and  communicating  the  meaning.  In  the  hunt 
for  a  forgotten  name,  the  throbbing,  restless  intent  becomes 
even  more  important  and  the  suggested  imagery  even  more 
accidental.  But  whether  the  meaning  is  concrete  or  ab- 
stract, the  intent-content  is  obviously  the  determining  aspect 
of  the  process  and  the  only  aspect  to  which  the  truth  con- 
ception is  relevant. 

With  this  passing  notice  of  the  concept  of  meaning,  we 
must  next  try  to  fix  the  concept  of  truth.  Here  there  is 
woeful  need  of  differentia.  In  the  first  place  it  is  well  to 
keep  in  mind  that  truth  and  meaning  are  not  coincident 
terms,  as  a  good  deal  of  the  discussion  of  to-day  seems  to  as- 
sume. Truth  is  only  one  species  of  meanings.  Esthetic 
meanings,  meanings  of  approval  and  disapproval,  not  to 
speak  of  the  whole  class  of  the  more  primitive  perceptual 
meanings,  do  not  involve  the  question  of  truth,  and  yet 
who  shall  deny  that  they  are  real  meanings  ?  The  enjoy- 
ment of  the  symphony  has  meaning,  as  well  as  the  testing 
of  the  hypothesis,  but  the  meanings  are  quite  different. 
What  then  constitutes  a  truth  meaning  ? 

Even  within  the  universe  of  thought  as  expressed  in 
language,  we  must  distinguish  the  meaning  of  a  proposition 
from  its  validity.  Taking  the  proposition  as  a  separate 
structure,  we  must  recognize  that  it  is  only  a  datum  for 
thought.  In  formal  logic,  we  are  not  concerned  with 
whether  propositions  are  materially  true  or  false.  We  in- 
vestigate merely  their  internal  meanings  and  their  relations. 
In  trying  to  understand  another  mind,  we  must  first  of  all 
get  his  meaning,  whether  we  agree  to  the  validity  of  his 

opinion  or  not.  We  say  :  "  I  see  what  you  mean,  but ." 

We  recognize  the  meaning  of  antiquated  theories  of  religion 


2O2  Truth  and  Reality 

and  of  science,  of  witchcraft  and  of  astrology,  though  we 
no  longer  recognize  their  validity. 

It  may  be  contended  that  what  we  really  mean  is  reality, 
and  that,  therefore,  there  can  be  final  distinction  between 

^ 

meaning  and  validity.  This  involves,  however,  an  assump- 
tion, as  regards  our  meaning  and  the  object  which  we 
mean,  that  we  cannot  accept  a  priori.  It  may  turn  out 
that  the  object  which  we  mean  is  only  more  of  our  mean- 
ing —  our  internal  meaning  enlarged  and  made  definite  in 
an  inclusive,  preexistent,  external  meaning.  But  that  this 
is  so  must  itself  be  proven  as  the  outcome  of  an  inductive 
process.  It  seems  to  us,  at  any  rate,  that  our  meanings 
must  mould  themselves  upon  the  carcass  of  reality  by  ex- 
ternal observation  and  experiment,  and  cannot  weave  the 
tissue  of  the  world  merely  out  of  themselves  by  implication, 
as  the  snail  secretes  his  shell.  For  us,  as  finites,  at  any 
rate,  the  difference  between  what  we  mean  and  what  is 
valid  may  involve  a  radical  wrench  to  our  meanings.  To 
be  valid,  meanings  must  not  merely  be  internally  consist- 
ent and  intelligible;  they  must  lead  to  a  reality  beyond 
themselves. 

If  we  use  meaning  in  the  sense  of  pragmatic  meaning  — 
the  difference  which  a  situation  makes  to  our  further  pro- 
cedure whether  practical  or  formal  —  then  there  can  be  no 
final  dualism  between  the  meaning  of  a  proposition  and  its 
truth.  The  meaning  which  moulds  itself  on  the  constitu- 
tion of  reality ;  which  leads  to  the  intended  consequences, 
is  precisely  the  valid  meaning.  But  even  here  we  must 
not  forget  that  our  internal  meanings  are  provisional  and 
that  they  become  true,  not  because  we  mean  them,  but 
because  they  enable  us  to  anticipate  and  control  their  ob- 
ject. This  should  prevent  us  from  being  arrogant  about 


Meaning  and  Validity  203 

Truth  in  the  singular  and  eternal  sense,  because  this  is 
at  best  an  ideal.  What  we  really  have,  on  any  theory, 
empirical  or  rationalistic,  are  "truths,"  tentative  leadings, 
halting  meanings,  which  in  part  and  darkly  help  us  to  take 
the  next  step. 

There  has  been  considerable  confusion  in  recent  discus- 
sion as  regards  the  definition  of  truth.  This  has  been 
owing  in  part  no  doubt  to  the  unorganized  state  of  prag- 
matism, but  still  more  to  its  caricature  by  its  critics.  It 
is  quite  true  that  we  cannot  define  truth  merely  as  that 
which  has  useful  consequences.  Castor  oil,  too,  has  use- 
ful consequences  under  certain  conditions.  Nor  is  truth 
useful  under  all  conditions ;  and  a  real  criterion  of  truth 
must  work  all  the  time.  It  must  give  us  point  for  point 
correspondence  so  far  as  the  relevant  features  of  the  situa- 
tion are  concerned.  We  sometimes  feel  that  we  have  to 
withhold  the  truth  of  his  condition  from  the  patient  for 
fear  of  jeopardizing  his  chances  at  a  critical  time.  A  father 
probably  would  not  thank  a  truthful  neighbor  for  enlight- 
ening his  son  as  to  his  father's  not  being  all  he  is  cracked 
up  to  be.  A  child's  idealizing  of  his  parent  seems,  on  the 
whole,  a  good  thing.  Only  in  Leibniz's  best  possible  uni- 
verse or  within  the  comprehensive  maw  of  an  idealistic 
absolute  does  it  follow  that  whatever  is  is  good,  and 
therefore  that  the  true  and  the  useful  coincide.  In  a 
world  as  pluralistic  and  plastic  as  our  social  world  is,  it 
may  very  well  happen  that  fiction  is  sometimes  better  than 
truth  ;  and  in  the  absence  of  idealization  most  of  us  would 
shrink  into  rather  bony  shadows.  Deception  may  be  an 
indispensable  means  to  social  progress.  The  fact  that  the 
true  and  the  useful  so  often  coincide,  and  that  the  useful 
must  largely  furnish  the  inspiration  for  the  true,  must  not 


2O4  Truth  and  Reality 

blind  us  to  the  contradictory  instances,  such  as  the  satisfy- 
ing of  curiosity  or  malice.  Only  the  devil  would  tell  the 
truth  under  some  circumstances.  Life  is  not  all  comedy. 
There  are  the  tragic,  slap-you-in-the-face  truths,  too,  the 
utility  of  which  lies  at  least  beyond  our  ken.  We  cannot 
be  said,  therefore,  to  have  defined  the  true  by  classifying  it 
under  the  useful. 

Nor  do  we  define  truth  by  stating  it  in  terms  of  "  satis- 
faction," even  though  satisfaction  or  fluency  of  some  kind 
should  turn  out  to  be  part  of  the  nature  of  truth.  I  see  no 
inherent  wrong  in  trying  to  state  truth  in  terms  of  our 
affective-volitional  nature,  as  well  as  in  intellectual  terms, 
provided  that  our  terms  define.  We  are  not  concerned  here 
with  the  question  which  is  the  more  fundamental  side  — 
whether  an  hypothesis  appears  to  agree  because  it  satisfies 
or  satisfies  because  it  agrees ;  psychologically  either  may 
be  true.  Our  intellectual  perception  influences  our  feel- 
ings; and  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  our  wishes  and 
feelings  influence  our  intellectual  perception.  They  con- 
dition our  emphasis  and  selection  of  data.  Human  nature 
is  not  divided  into  water-tight  compartments.  In  either 
case  we  must  speak  in  finite  terms  —  what  seems  to  agree 
and  what  now  satisfies.  One  side  of  human  nature  has  no 
more  finality  than  the  other.  In  the  long  run,  no  doubt, 
only  real  agreement  seems  agreement  and  only  real  agree- 
ment satisfies  the  truth  demand.  This  would  of  course 
include  the  cases  where  our  faith,  our  affective-volitional 
nature,  is  a  creative  factor  in  making  the  agreement  come 
true,  as  well  as  cases  where  the  facts  are  indifferent  to  our 
faith,  "  for  who  by  taking  thought  can  add  one  cubit  to  his 
stature  ?"  But  we  are  concerned  now  with  what  makes  an 
idea  true.  And  while  the  truth  activity  has,  no  doubt,  its 


Meaning  and  Validity  205 

characteristic  tone  of  satisfaction,  it  is  not  this  tone  which 
makes  the  idea  true.  We  have  the  satisfaction  whenever 
we  believe  that  we  have  attained  the  truth,  though  we  are 
often  mistaken,  as  shown  by  further  experience.  And  we 
could  not  have  a  mistaken  criterion  of  truth. 

If  we  define  truth  in  terms  of  satisfaction,  we  should  at 
least  state  what  kind  of  satisfaction  or  what  sort  of  fulfill- 
ment of  purpose,  because  otherwise  we  would  not  distin- 
guish truth  satisfaction  from  esthetic  or  moral  or  any  other 
type  ,of  satisfaction.  In  these,  too,  we  have  selection, 
simplification  and  ideal  construction ;  and  yet  these  are  not 
truth  attitudes.  What  are,  then,  the  differentia  of  truth 
"  satisfaction,"  if  we  state  truth  in  terms  of  value  ?  It  is 
not  merely  what  our  ancestors  felt  or  what  our  great  grand- 
children are  going  to  feel,  nor  is  it  determined  by  intensity 
or  duration.  It  is  not  enough  to  state  it  as  social  value, 
because  other  types  of  value  too  are  social.  Nor  must  it 
be  merely  the  satisfaction  that  truth  leads  to,  because  this 
need  not  be  truth  at  all.  It  may  be  mystical  trance  or 
sleep.  The  value  of  truth  is  not  simply  its  use,  as  some 
writers  seem  to  hold ;  but  the  feeling  which  characterizes 
truth  or  accompanies  the  truth  attitude.  And  this  attitude 
consists  in  the  termination  of  the  idea,  purpose  or  expect- 
ancy in  its  complementary  facts,  the  agreement  of  the  par- 
ticular hypothesis  or  suspicion  with  the  reality  which  it 
intends  or  points  to. 

To  call  this  termination  of  search,  this  equilibrium  of 
hypothesis  or  suspicion,  thus  terminating  in  evidence, 
"  satisfaction,"  in  the  sense  of  a  utilitarian  good,  needs  quali- 
fication. This  implies  that  truth  is  always  an  unqualified 
good.  Yet  in  the  uncertainty  may  lie  the  only  hope,  and 
never  to  know  may  be  blessed.  A  man  I  know  was  a  long 


2O6  Truth  and  Reality 

time  in  uncertainty  as  to  the  suicide  of  his  son.  The  alter- 
native hypothesis  kept  him  up,  but  the  hypothesis  of  suicide 
finally  terminated  in  facts.  The  man  became  a  perma- 
nent melancholiac.  The  only  "  satisfaction  "  of  such  a  truth 
is  that  it  puts  a  stop  to  uncertainty;  that  one  dread  alter- 
native with  its  black  emotion  finally  possesses  the  field. 
The  intellectual  "  satisfaction  "  here  runs  counter  to  any 
moral  satisfaction  surely.  It  condemns  the  world  as  evil, 
so  far  as  that  individual  is  concerned.  A  man  who  has 
become  addicted  to  opiates  or  passed  through  certain 
kinds  of  vice  has  a  certain  knowledge  that  the  normal  man 
does  not  possess ;  but  such  a  knowledge  is  a  doubtful  good. 

The  "  satisfaction  "  of  truth,  then,  is  a  coefficient  of  the 
terminating  of  an  idea  in  a  certain  reality  which  it  intends 
or  suspects,  hopes  for  or  fears.  It  may  be  good  or  it  may 
be  evil  or  it  may  be  mixed.  It  takes  its  coloring  from  the 
nature  of  the  situation  —  the  idea  and  its  termination.  In 
general  it  simply  means  equilibrium  after  doubt  or  intellec- 
tual readjustment,  a  termination  of  search  and  uncertainty 
so  far  as  that  particular  hypothesis  is  concerned.  Truth 
value  gets  its  tinge  from  this  particular  agreement  or  ter- 
mination. To  speak  of  such  termination  as  fulfillment  and 
satisfaction  is  born  of  the  same  undiscriminating  optimism 
which  exhibited  the  trophies  at  Delphi. 

Even  in  using  terms  of  expectancy,  as  I  have  above,  I 
feel  that  I  have  overstated  the  subjective  "leading"  of 
truth,  for  facts  may  be  forced  upon  our  acknowledgment 
which  we  can  neither  be  said  to  have  intended  nor  sus- 
pected. They  may  drop  from  a  clear  sky.  In  our  plural- 
istic, changing  world  we  do  not  always  have  opportunity  to 
plan  for  the  facts  nor  even  to  suspect  them.  The  facts 
sometimes  select  us  instead  of  our  selecting  them.  They 


Meaning  and  Validity  207 

sometimes  violate  all  our  fundamental  interests,  outside  of 
the  cognitive.  In  the  case  of  the  news  of  our  friend  having 
perished  in  a  railroad  accident,  the  news  does  not  come  as 
fulfillment  of  purpose.  If  so,  we  ought  to  be  tried  for 
murder  in  the  first  degree.  Truth  here  means  chaos,  the 
defeat  of  expectancy.  The  particular  ideational  setting 
here  is  selected  or  forced  by  the  environment  In  most 
human  lives  the  unwelcome,  unintended  facts  are  probably 
as  numerous  as  those  planned  for.  Satisfied  or  unsatisfied, 
we  have  to  accommodate  ourselves  to  the  new  events.  But 
if  the  hedonic  value  of  truth  is  determined  by  the  particu- 
lar agreement  of  our  idea  with  its  reality,  then  the  nature 
of  this  agreement  with  reality  becomes  the  important  thing 
to  investigate  for  any  real  light  on  truth  —  its  relation  to 
its  object  and  the  manner  of  testing,  rather  than  the  he- 
donic tone  of  the  psychological  situation. 

Is  there  an  immediate  test  of  truth,  the  result  of  the 
mere  inspecting  of  a  meaning  or  proposition  and  without 
any  need  of  examining  its  relation  to  a  larger  world  ? 
There  always  will  be  people,  no  doubt,  who  will  insist 
upon  the  a  priori  certainty  of  some  propositions  or  axioms. 
But  what  do  we  mean  by  such  certainty  and  what  guaranty 
does  it  have  ?  Some  have  found  such  certainty  in  the 
authority  of  the  mystical  illumination  of  certain  moments. 
Even  William  James  argues  that  such  mystical  illumination 
is  authoritative  for  him  who  has  the  experience,  even  if  not 
coercive  over  others.  But  he  also  admits,  at  least  by  his 
illustrations,  that  such  a  feeling  of  illumination,  whether 
artificially  or  spontaneously  produced,  may  be  the  merest 
insanity.  It  would  seem  to  be  impossible,  so  far  as  the 
mystical  states  go,  to  judge  between  sense  and  nonsense ; 
and  therefore  it  is  hard  to  see  how  such  conscious  states 


208  Truth  and  Reality 

can  be  authoritative  or  valid  in  their  own  right  in  any 
epistemological  sense.  They  may  be  mystically  and  es- 
thetically  satisfying  and  we  may  choose  to  abide  by  them, 
but  that  does  not  make  them  valid.  The  truth  of  such 
states  must  be  found  in  their  being  socially  applicable,  in 
their  ability  to  meet  and  organize  the  data  of  waking  ex- 
perience. A  truth  valid  only  for  the  one  who  has  it  can 
hardly  be  called  truth.  Rich  as  such  states  may  be  in 
emotional  meaning  ;  though  they  do  transport  the  individ- 
ual who  has  them  to  the  seventh  heaven,  yet  they  are 
verified  only  as  they  agree  with  further  experience,  as 
they  permit  of  being  translated  into  the  prose  of  waking 
life.  Mystical  certainty  simply  amounts  to  saying  that  if 
a  man  feels  that  way,  he  feels  that  way,  though  it  be  the 
merest  nonsense.  Luminousness  may  be  a  part  of  the 
truth  experience,  but  it  does  not  make  it  valid. 

Others  again  have  insisted,  according  to  temperament, 
upon  the  dry  light  or  upon  the  feeling  of  fitness  or  upon 
the  categorical  character  of  certain  propositions,  especially 
the  mathematical  and  moral.  But  this  intuitional  or  cate- 
gorical certainty  is  simply  another  name  for  believing  a 
thing.  Our  belief  may  have  an  instinctive  basis  or  it  may 
be  due  to  indissoluble  association;  but  in  either  event  it 
does  not  prove  anything,  except  that  we  have  it.  Even 
the  categorical  vehemence  of  a  Kant  is  not  sufficient  to 
make  traditional  beliefs  valid.  The  serious  inroad  upon 
the  mathematical  axioms,  especially  Euclid's  list,  which 
seemed  for  centuries  so  categorically  and  dryly  certain, 
should  give  us  warning  not  to  put  our  trust  too  implicitly 
upon  traditional  certainties.  Axioms,  after  all,  are  gen- 
eralizations from  experience;  and  however  intuitive  they 
may  become  in  the  process  of  individual  and  race  history, 


Meaning  and  Validity  209 

they  can  be  validated  only  with  reference  to  the  procedure 
of  experience,  individual  and  social.  The  a  priori  certainty 
of  the  law  of  identity  and  of  the  law  of  contradiction  resolves 
itself  into  hypothetical  tautology  apart  from  experience. 
If  a  thing  or  meaning  is  the  same,  it  is  the  same ;  and  if  it 
is  the  same,  it  is  not  other.  Whether  there  is  such  a  thing 
as  identity  or  not  must  be  determined  by  experience.  Even 
our  more  positive  "love  for  the  wholeness  of  things,"  which 
is  the  root  of  scientific  endeavor,  is  not  valid  except  as  it 
can^be  realized,  however  partially,  in  experience.  The  im- 
mediate inspection  of  our  ideas,  therefore,  is  not  sufficient 
to  establish  the  truth  of  those  ideas,  except  as  we  are  con- 
cerned merely  with  the  Cartesian  axiom  of  the  existence  of 
such  facts  in  consciousness.  It  cannot  furnish  a  final  test 
of  validity. 

The  impossibility  of  conceiving  the  contrary  carries  us 
no  further.  This  is  true  in  all  real  belief.  A  man  re- 
cently told  me  that  he  was  so  steeped  in  the  doctrine  of 
the  Trinity  that  he  could  not  conceive  anything  else ;  yet 
on  questioning  him  I  found  that  the  doctrine  with  him 
was  merely  emotional,  and  had  no  intellectual  significance. 
Sometimes  these  axioms,  the  contrary  of  which  cannot  be 
conceived,  have  taken  an  entirely  contrary  form  in  differ- 
ent minds.  Hence  the  antinomies  which  men  like  Zeno, 
Kant  and  Spencer  have  used  to  discredit  finite  knowledge. 
Thus  one  holds  that  reality  must  be  finite,  another  that  it 
must  be  infinite.  One  holds  that  it  must  be  infinitely  di- 
visible, another  that  it  consists  of  indivisible  individuals  or 
is  an  individual  whole.  One  holds  that  cause  and  effect 
must  be  identical,  another  that  they  must  be  different,  etc. 
Men  like  Spencer  simply  lie  down  and  allow  themselves 
to  be  buried  by  such  venerable  contradictions.  Each  side 


2IO  Truth  and  Reality 

of  the  antinomy  retained  its  force  for  him,  and  so  there 
was  nothing  to  do  but  doubt  his  reason.  And  Spencer's 
reason  was  very  inadequate.  How  many  of  such  musts, 
the  contrary  of  which  he  cannot  conceive,  a  man  has  de- 
pends mostly  upon  his  stupidity  and  lack  of  imagination. 
So  far  as  mere  logic  is  concerned,  we  must  hold  with 
the  ancient  Protagoras :  "  On  every  question  there  are  two 
speeches,  which  stand  in  opposition  to  one  another."  The 
impossibility  of  the  contrary  appears  only  when  we  set  our- 
selves a  definite  purpose,  adopt  a  certain  universe  of  dis- 
course, formal  or  empirical,  with  its  definite  constitution. 
Thus  conceiving  the  contrary  of  the  law  of  consistency  is 
impossible  within  the  universe  of  truth,  though  we  can 
conceive  a  universe  —  that  of  absolute  dissimilarity  or  of 
absolute  chance,  —  in  which  the  law  of  consistency  is  not 
applicable. 

Validity  can  only  be  stated  as  the  agreement  of  an  idea 
or  belief  with  its  reality.  The  idea  may  be  selective  of  the 
reality  or  the  reality  may  force  the  idea.  The  feeling  may 
be  one  of  satisfaction  or  dissatisfaction,  according  as  the 
reality  we  must  acknowledge  fits  or  thwarts  our  conative 
tendencies,  but  'tis  true  whether  'tis  pity  'tis  true  or  joy  un- 
speakable. Nor  does  the  psychological  motive  or  interest, 
which  prompts  the  search  for  the  particular  truth,  alter 
the  truth  relation.  Whether  the  motives  for  investigating 
the  chemical  properties  of  strychnine  be  those  of  inventing 
a  superior  tonic  or  of  finding  a  new  way  of  committing  mur- 
der, the  truth  as  regards  the  properties  remains  the  same. 
It  has  sometimes  been  argued  that,  because  the  motive 
for  seeking  truth  often  lies  in  our  affective-volitional  nature, 
therefore  the  test  of  truth  lies  in  the  satisfaction  of  this 
side  of  our  nature.  But  whether  our  motive  for  seeking 


Meaning  and   Validity  211 

for  truth  lies  in  our  instinct  for  gain,  revenge  or  sympathy, 
the  test  is  precisely  the  same  as  though  the  motive  lay  in 
impartial  curiosity  or  "  love  of  the  wholeness  of  things." 
In  any  case,  truth  consists  in  the  tallying,  whether  coercively 
or  constructively,  of  the  idea  with  its  reality. 

This  agreement  may  be  merely  formal,  if  our  cognitive 
purpose  is  merely  formal.  Our  syllogistic  reasoning  is 
valid  if  the  conclusion  agrees,  according  to  logical  rules, 
with  the  premises.  In  order  to  have  objective  validity, 
however,  more  is  needed  than  formal  agreement  or  concep- 

t 

tual  necessity.  The  novel,  too,  must  be  consistent.  Nestor 
and  Ulysses  are  beautifully  self-harmonious  characters. 
Truth,  in  the  objective  sense,  must  agree  with  a  prior 
reality.  Consistency  with  what?  becomes  the  question. 
And  it  must  be  consistency  with  the  reality  selected  or 
which  selects  us.  This  may  be  a  philological  root  or  a 
chemical  substance  or  an  earthquake.  The  scientific  hy- 
pothesis is  valid  when  it  terminates  in  the  experiences 
which  it  intends,  when  we  must  act  as  if  it  were  true. 
Else  it  must  be  revised.  But  validity  in  any  case  means 
agreement,  whether  of  ideas  with  other  ideas,  as  in  formal 
reasoning,  or  with  facts  of  a  perceptual  and  individual  kind, 
as  in  concrete  truth. 

When  the  agreement  can  be  shared  with  other  egos,  we 
regard  the  validity  as  to  that  extent  corroborated.  Truth 
is  a  social  institution,  if  not  at  the  time  of  its  discovery,  at 
least  in  the  long  run.  We  are  entitled  to  no  private  laws 
of  logic  nor  to  any  private  perceptions.  When,  therefore, 
the  argument  or  the  experiment  wins  the  agreement  of 
contemporary  investigators  or  checks  up  with  social  expe- 
rience, our  scientific  nervousness  is  greatly  relieved.  So- 
cial agreement  has  often  seemed  the  final  test  of  truth. 


212  Truth  and  Reality 

Individual  judgment  seems  insignificant,  when  pitted  against 
the  funded  and  approved  knowledge  of  the  race. 

But  the  individual  sometimes  proves  wiser  than  the 
society  of  his  day.  What  social  prejudice  prevents  con- 
temporaries from  seeing,  the  chosen  one  of  Jehovah  sees. 
And  he  takes  his  stand  upon  his  insight  —  sometimes  rea- 
soned, sometimes  quite  intuitional.  Truth,  therefore,  not 
only  must  seem  to  agree  now  with  individual  or  social 
experience.  Truth  must  agree  with  the  future.  Social 
agreement,  owing  to  the  variable  and  complex  character  of 
human  nature,  does  not  cover  the  whole  field  of  the  inner 
attitudes  of  the  various  individuals.  The  overtones  of  in- 
dividual natures  may  vary  vastly;  and  while  the  census 
tables  deal  with  us  on  the  basis  of  averages,  the  individual 
differences  may  be  the  more  significant  facts  for  the  prog- 
ress of  the  race.  It  is  only  through  individual  variations, 
such  as  the  great  geniuses  of  mankind,  and  their  imitation 
by  society,  that  higher  social  levels,  intellectual  and  moral, 
are  possible. 

Individual  and  social  selection  alike  are  subject  to  selec- 
tion by  the  future  —  to  cosmic  selection.  While  we  mean 
what  we  mean,  while  our  insight  may  satisfy  us  for  the 
time  being,  this  does  not  prove  the  ultimate  validity  of  our 
present  meanings.  The  historic  method  has  emphasized 
nothing  so  much  as  the  relativity  of  our  finite  view-points, 
individual  and  social.  The  evolutionary  process,  having 
set  us  our  program  by  the  categories  which  it  has  furnished, 
reacts  upon  our  rational  selection,  transforms,  eliminates 
or  selects  our  individual  and  institutional  purposes.  The 
individual  or  social  satisfaction  of  our  meanings  does  not 
guarantee  their  survival,  not  even  with  universal  agreement, 
at  any  one  time.  No  axioms  could  have  been  more  univer- 


Meaning  and  Validity  213 

sal  than  the  geocentric  view  of  the  world  and  that  of  "  an 
eye  for  an  eye  and  a  tooth  for  a  tooth."  Yet  even  these 
have  not  proved  permanent.  The  process  is  ever  furnish- 
ing new  variations  and,  in  its  growing  social  complexity,  is 
enforcing  new  survival  conditions.  The  old  science  be- 
comes mythology  and  the  old  conceptions  of  fair  play  van- 
dalism. An  idea  o'i  meaning,  to  be  absolutely  valid,  must 
be  tested  by  passing  through  the  sifting  process  of  the 
stream  of  human  natures.  Each  generation  must  add  its 
proviso  of  time.  It  must  not  shackle  the  future.  Our  pres- 
ent formal  demands,  growing  out  of  our  instinctive  and 
social  heritage,  must  be  treated  as  hypotheses,  though  not 
necessarily  conscious  of  themselves,  to  be  tested  by  the  on- 
going of  human  experience,  individual  and  social.  This 
stream  of  processes,  moreover,  is  not  a  mere  chance  affair 
as  regards  its  ultimate  value  and  meaning,  but  is  determined 
by  an  objective  formal  constitution  of  the  whole  universe. 
This  I  have  discussed  elsewhere.1 

Thus  cosmic  selection,  which  is  responsible  for  our  ten- 
dencies and  demands,  reacts  again  upon  the  products  of 
the  rational  process.  It  determines  what  ideals  or  pur- 
poses shall  have  a  place  in  the  process  in  the  long 
run. 

1  See  International  Journal  of  Ethics,  Vol.  XVII,  p.  454  ft 


CHAPTER  XII 
TRUTH  AND  AGREEMENT 

BOTH  realists  and  idealists  have  joined  in  maintaining 
that  truth  is  agreement  with  reality.  But  they  have  failed 
to  state  the  nature  of  this  agreement.  Is  truth  a  duplicate 
of  reality  or  is  it  merely  symbolic  of  reality  ?  If  the  latter, 
what  is  the  rationale  of  inventing  this  symbolism  ?  Dog- 
matic realism  and  dogmatic  idealism  alike  fail  to  break  up 
reality  and  so  fail  to  show  the  different  meaning  of  agree- 
ment, according  as  truth  is  a  copying  process  or  is  an  arti- 
ficial device.  I  hope  to  make  these  problems  a  little  clearer 
in  this  chapter. 


The  problem  of  correspondence  was  a  simple  affair  for 
naive  realism,  because  naive  realism  dealt  with  only  one 
kind  of  stuff,  one  grade  of  reality.  Whether  it  is  a  case  of 
like  perceiving  like,  as  with  Empedocles ;  or  opposites  per- 
ceiving opposites :  cold  perceiving  hot ;  the  light,  the  dark, 
etc.,  as  with  Anaxagoras,  we  still  remain  within  the  one 
nexus  of  changes.  For  both  the  idea,  which  strives  to  know, 
and  the  object  to  be  known,  are  conceived  as  physical  facts 
and  the  act  of  knowledge  itself  as  a  physical  change.  This 
is  equally  true  of  the  effluences  of  Empedocles,  the  images 
of  Democri^tus,  and  the  forms  Aristotle  and  the  School- 
men, with  the  passive  imprint  which  these  forms  are  sup- 
posed to  make  upon  the  wax  tablet  of  the  mind.  With  a 

214 


Truth  and  Agreement  215 

sharp  distinction  between  mind  and  body,  which  took  defi- 
nite form  with  Augustine  and  was  revived  by  Descartes, 
the  difficulties  as  to  how  one  set  of  processes  can  make  a 
difference  to  another  set  of  processes  thickened.  So  we 
have  the  terminism  of  Occam  and  the  phenomenalism  of 
Hume  and  Kant.  There  can,  on  this  view,  be  no  real 
imitation  by  knowledge  of  reality,  for  knowledge  moves 
within  a  world  of  its  own.  It  is  at  most  a  sign  lan- 
guage. We  can  know  nothing  about  the  real  world.  We 
know  it  only  as  it  terminates  in  our  subjective  sensa- 
tions and  is  elaborated  in  our  experience.  There  can,  how- 
ever, be  phenomenal  verification  or  anticipation  within 
experience.  The  world  of  shadows,  also,  to  use  Platonic 
language,  has  its  uniformities,  which  make  prediction  pos- 
sible. If  we  are  doomed  to  the  world  of  shadows,  we  can 
at  least  get  ready  for  future  shadows. 

Idealism,  in  insisting  again  upon  one  kind  of  stuff,  i.e., 
mind  stuff,  tries  to  return  to  the  original  simplicity  of  like 
acting  upon  like.  So  long  as  the  question  of  the  ego  is 
not  raised,  the  problem  is  easily  stated  as  merely  purposive 
realization  or  logical  connection  within  one  context  or  unity 
of  thought  When  the  question  is  raised,  however,  as  to 
whose  experience  or  unity,  the  problem  grows  more  diffi- 
cult. The  idealist  must  either  raise  himself  into  a  solipsis- 
tic  absolute  or,  in  modestly  recognizing  his  own  finitude, 
face  the  dualism  of  an  internal  and  external  meaning,  and 
struggle  over  the  seeming  fragmentariness  and  darkness 
of  our  world. 

A  new  theory  of  knowledge  has  been  developed  in  re- 
cent times  by  William  James  and  others,  which  tries  to 
avoid  the  idealistic  difficulty  and  presumption  by  treating 
knowledge  as  merely  an  instrument  having  no  relevancy 


2i6  Truth  and  Reality 

to  the  object  to  be  known,  but  being  valid  in  case  it  can 
be  exchanged,  in  the  course  of  the  process,  for  immediate  ex- 
perience, as  wares  are  exchanged  for  gold.  While  such  a 
theory,  with  abundant  illustrations  from  natural  science, 
accounts  for  how  knowledge  can  control  the  world  of  pro- 
cesses, it  leaves  us  in  the  dark  as  to  the  real  question  — 
the  relevancy  of  knowledge  to  its  object. 

II 

Before  we  can  have  purposive  selection  and  correspond- 
ence, our  selection  is  determined  by  our  instinctive  ten- 
dencies. The  infant  does  not  have  any  definite  program ; 
it  is  not  as  yet  a  self  and  so  is  not  concerned  about  self- 
realization.  It  is  so  constituted,  however,  as  to  respond  in 
characteristic  ways  to  certain  stimuli,  such  as  moving  things, 
bright  things,  loud  things,  things  to  eat,  to  grasp,  to  be 
afraid  of,  etc.  There  is  no  question  of  intention  here  and 
therefore  no  question  of  truth.  The  infant,  as  the  result  of 
the  evolutionary  process,  is  such  a  slot  as  can  be  set  off  by 
just  such  pennies.  What  adaptation,  fitness  or  correspond- 
ence to  its  environment  there  is,  means  fitness  or  corre- 
spondence only  to  a  more  developed  stage  of  experience. 
Its  movements  do  indeed  show  a  certain  degree  of  adapta- 
tion, its  sense-responses  may  be  said  to  correspond  to 
stimuli  of  so  many  vibrations  per  second.  But  they  do 
not  mean  correspondence  to  the  infant. 

Agreement  means  agreement  only  when  we  intention- 
ally select  in  the  realization  of  a  certain  purpose.  Only 
then  does  truth  or  error  exist.  If  I  point  to  Peter  when 
I  mean  Paul,  to  white  when  I  mean  black,  I  have  failed 
to  carry  out  my  intent  and  so  have  erred.  To  corre- 
spond or  agree  means  to  realize  my  purpose  or  at  any 


Truth  and  Agreement  217 

rate  to  be  able  to  act  as  if  my  hypothesis  were  true. 
Correspondence,  however,  has  a  twofold  significance,  the 
instrumental  relation  of  the  knowing  attitude  to  its  ob- 
ject and  that  of  sharing,  to  use  a  Platonic  term. 

In  so  far  as  reflective  thought  sets  its  own  conditions, 
irrespective  of  the  inner  meaning  of  the  processes  to 
which  it  refers,  aiming  simply  at  prediction  or  control 
of  the  object  as  a  means  to  its  own  purposes  —  in  so  far 
thought  is  instrumental.  Whether  the  object  itself  has 
any*  meaning  or  not,  such  meaning  or  claim  is  ignored. 
And  thought  must  always  be  instrumental  when  it  deals 
with  that  which  is  immediate  and  which,  therefore,  is 
transformed  and  done  violence  to  in  being  dealt  with  re- 
flectively. This  is  equally  true  of  brute  immediacy  and 
of  immediacy  on  the  higher  esthetic  level,  which  pre- 
supposes thought  life.  If  reality,  therefore,  in  its  ultimate 
meaning  must  be  conceived  as  mystical  appreciation, 
which  passes  knowledge,  as  the  mystics  from  Plotinus  to 
Bradley  have  insisted,  then  knowledge  would  always  need 
to  be  instrumental.  Again,  in  bringing  our  categories  — 
the  result  of  our  instinctive  equipment  and  social,  historic 
setting  —  to  bear  upon  the  sense  material  which  furnishes 
us  with  our  data  of  nature,  with  its  coexistences  and  se- 
quences, we  can  hope  to  have  only  instrumental  knowl- 
edge. We  cannot  agree  that  because  nature  can  be  made 
to  realize  purposes,  it  is  itself  purposive ;  any  more  than 
because  a  knife  cuts  meat,  it  must  itself  be  meat.  It  must 
indeed  be  something,  i.e.,  it  must  be  capable  of  making 
predictable  differences  to  us.  But  we  cannot  treat  it  as 
purposive.  If  there  is  purpose  governing  nature,  it  must 
be  extra-natural,  determining  survival.  The  old  idea  of 
correspondence,  which  Kant  subjected  to  such  searching 


218  Truth  and  Reality 

criticism,  deals  with  this  relation  of  the  concept  to  the 
non- reflective  or  physical  world.  Here  it  is  easy  to  show 
that  there  can  be  no  internal  correspondence,  or  copying  of 
meaning,  as  the  processes  which  we  investigate  have  no 
inwardness.  We  make  the  conceptual  system  of  nature  — 
unify  it,  in  obedience  to  our  tendencies,  on  the  one  hand, 
and  the  data  of  immediate  experience,  on  the  other,  so  as 
to  meet  the  requirements  of  the  environment  and,  so  far 
as  possible,  control  it  for  our  needs.  We  are  here  limited 
to  the  external  continuities  and  qualities  of  nature.  We 
cannot  acknowledge  things  as  having  a  halo  of  meaning  or 
value  of  their  own. 

Sometimes  even  knowledge  of  ideal  objects  is  legitimately 
of  this  instrumental  kind.  Treating  the  circle  as  made  up 
of  infinitesimal  straight  lines,  though  convenient,  does  not 
correspond  even  with  our  ideal  reality.  The  census  tables 
do  not  correspond  to  any  real  order.  They  are  sorted  facts 
for  an  artificial  purpose.  Sometimes  we  ignore  the  claims 
of  the  reflective  consciousness,  because  we  regard  it  as  crim- 
inal or  pernicious  to  our  standards  of  truth  and  right.  But 
sometimes  we  ignore  the  claims  of  other  meanings  because 
of  our  moral  blindness.  The  cardinal  crime,  the  crime  of 
crimes,  as  Kant  has  shown,  is  to  neglect  the  inner  signifi- 
cance of  our  fellow-man  and  to  treat  him  merely  as  a  thing. 
What  we  respect  as  having  a  claim  on  its  own  account 
must  differ  widely,  too,  in  different  stages  of  development. 
For  the  savage,  what  is  outside  of  the  tribe  has  no  meaning 
which  needs  to  be  respected.  On  the  other  hand,  nature 
phenomena,  ghosts,  etc.,  are  treated  with  more  than  human 
respect.  In  general  we  find  that  it  is  easy  to  recognize  a 
meaning  if  it  agrees  with  our  own,  but  difficult  the  greater 
the  divergence, 


Truth  and  Agreement  219 

Knowledge  may  be  instrumental,  then,  for  two  reasons. 
It  may  be  instrumental  because  it  belongs  to  another  order 
of  reality  from  the  object  it  strives  to  know.  It  may  be  a 
systematic  arrangement,  in  the  service  of  our  purposes,  of 
facts  which  themselves  know  no  system.  This  must  hold 
wherever  science  deals  with  non-reflective  facts,  as  in 
the  physical  sciences.  It  holds  of  the  psychological  sci- 
ences, too,  when  they  are  not  dealing  with  processes  of 
the  reflective  or  meaningful  grade,  or  when  they  are  de- 
composing the  reflective  attitude  for  purposes  of  naturalistic 
description.  In  so  far  as  our  analysis  and  reconstruction 
must  always  fall  short  of  the  real  object,  all  our  knowledge 
becomes  infected  more  or  less  with  the  instrumental  char- 
acter. We  can  never,  in  our  description,  give  the  complete 
equivalents  of  the  real  gold  or  the  real  Socrates.  This 
can  be  only  when  our  purpose  creates  its  own  object.  Else 
we  have  to  be  satisfied  with  such  aspects  of  the  situation  as 
will  suffice  for  the  leading  of  truth. 

Ill 

Some  objects  of  knowledge  must  be  recognized  as 
having  a  meaning  of  their  own,  a  rational  purpose  and 
value,  which  we  must  acknowledge.  Even  here,  knowledge, 
to  be  sure,  must  be  in  some  degree  instrumental,  as  we 
have  seen ;  but  this  is  only  incidental,  a  stage  in  the  process 
of  sharing  or  sympathizing  with  the  object.  The  problem 
here  is  no  longer  one  of  mere  manipulation.  The  corre- 
spondence here  cannot  be  exhausted  in  the  one-sided 
relation  of  hypothesis  to  immediacy  within  the  process  of 
individual  experience.  The  judging  attitude  here  is  a 
different  one  from  that  of  means  and  end.  The  fulfillment 
of  our  purpose  here  is  conditioned  upon  partaking  of  an 


22O  Truth  and  Reality 

extra-individual  realm  of  meanings,  respecting  and  sym- 
pathizing with  them.  We  do  not  want  to  make  over  or 
control  Shakespeare's  Hamlet  or  the  Sistine  Madonna  or 
the  friend  that  we  love.  We  want  to  understand  and 
appreciate  them.  Our  knowledge,  when  it  is  concerned 
with  social  or  ideal  structures,  is  primarily  of  this  sharing 
character.  It  is  not  the  business  of  the  historian  to  make 
over  the  past,  but  to  understand  it  or  share  its  meaning. 
Even  when  our  aim  is  that  of  the  practical  reformer  or 
when  we  must  revise  the  scientific  hypothesis,  it  is  first 
incumbent  upon  us  to  understand  or  share  the  ideals  which 
we  would  revise  or  reinterpret.  To  fail  to  recognize  in  the 
universe  any  purpose  but  our  own,  is  to  be  a  bore  or  a 
criminal.  Some  individuals  must  be  respected  as  having 
a  meaning  of  their  own  and  cannot  be  treated  merely  as 
things,  if  we  would  live  fairly  and,  in  the  end,  accomplish 
our  purposes.  To  be  sure,  our  limitations  as  finite  beings 
and  as  part  of  the  time-process  makes  such  sharing  diffi- 
cult; but  it  remains,  nevertheless,  a  real  aim.  Plato  has  a 
word  for  us,  as  well  as  the  modern  instrumentalist. 

In  instrumental  knowledge,  as  we  have  seen,  the  ques- 
tion is  merely  how  the  facts  seem  to  us ;  how  they  can  be 
controlled  by  us;  whether  our  concepts  terminate  in  per- 
ceptions. Not  so  in  the  knowledge  of  the  sharing  type. 
Here  the  truth  attitude  is  not  merely  an  artificial  tool,  like 
an  astronomical  ellipse  or  a  census  table.  It  is  not  a  piece- 
meal selection  of  external  qualities  and  relations  which  are 
serviceable  as  leadings  to  the  concrete  processes  which  we 
strive  to  anticipate  and  control.  We  must  imitate,  not 
merely  externally,  but  share  and  acknowledge,  soul 
confronting  soul,  the  individual's  own  meaning  in  its 
unique  wholeness.  Only  when  social  communication  of 


Truth  and  Agreement  221 

mind  with  mind  results  in  such  sympathy  and  copying  do 
we  have  real  knowledge  of  selves.  In  so  far  as  the  knowing 
attitude  here  can  be  completely  realized,  it  is  no  longer  of 
reality ;  but  it  is  reality.  To  know  the  meaning  of  Hamlet 
is  to  have  the  reality  of  Hamlet  Leibniz's  monads  are  a 
splendid  illustration  of  a  universe  which  might  exist  in 
many  copies. 

To  be  sure,  here,  too,  the  concept  or  hypothesis  must 
terminate  in  immediate  experiences,  present  or  future, 
within  our  individual  history.  But  these  become  signs  of 

• 

another  reality,  which  we  strive  to  reach.  We  do  not  stop 
with  the  external  characters  —  the  printed  words  or  spoken 
sounds.  These  become  symbolic  merely  —  carriers  of  the 
meaning.  The  difference  in  the  two  attitudes  may  be 
said  to  be  a  metaphysical  difference,  i.e.,  a  difference  as 
regards  the  ultimate  intent  of  the  knowing  process,  rather 
than  methodological.  The  finite  test  of  the  corre- 
spondence in  either  case,  the  test  available  from  moment 
to  moment  in  individual  life  —  whether  in  knowledge  of 
the  instrumental  or  sharing  type,  is  an  internal  test  or  the 
corresponding  of  our  purpose  or  hypothesis  with  the  on- 
going of  experience.  It  means  an  attitude  of  fulfillment 
or  forced  acknowledgment  in  this  ongoing. 

The  knowing  process,  when  it  deals  with  psychological 
unities,  is  really  valid  only  when  it  reproduces  or  copies 
the  object,  is  the  nature  of  the  object.  The  only  valid 
hypothesis  about  a  reflective  object  is  the  attitude  that 
acknowledges  the  meaning  of  the  object  and  succeeds  in 
sharing  it  —  aims  beyond  sense-experience  at  its  meta- 
physical reality.  Whether  this  aim  or  intent  is  true  or 
not  must  be  tested,  as  in  the  instrumental  case,  with  ref- 
erence to  further  experience.  But  this  attitude,  if  true, 


222  Truth  and  Reality 

terminates  in  sharing  and  not  in  mere  perceptions  and 
their  uniformities.  Another  center  of  experience  is  ac- 
knowledged, which  has  put  its  prior  stamp  upon  our  self- 
stamped  facts.  The  attitudes  in  the  cases  of  sharable 
and  non-sharable  realities  are  built  out  in  different  ways ; 
the  former  has  over-beliefs  that  the  latter  does  not  have, 
and  so  requires  a  different  verification  —  a  verification  in- 
cluding the  over-beliefs.  When  such  sharing  is  impossible 
we  must  be  satisfied  with  such  artificial  or  phenomenal 
correspondence  as  the  uniformity  of  our  perceptions  makes 
possible. 

IV 

This  theory  of  copying  must  be  distinguished  from  the 
theory  of  the  cinematographic  copy  of  the  flux  of  the 
universe,  advanced  by  Henry  Bergson.  In  the  first  place, 
the  copying  of  which  we  are  speaking  is  a  real  imitation  of 
reality.  We  follow  its  stages  of  cumulative  meaning  as 
revealed  in  another  mind  history  or  its  products.  In  the 
second  place,  the  cinematographic  copy,  at  best,  would  be 
cumbersome  and  useless,  even  for  practical  purposes.  It 
could  furnish  no  leading  to  the  will  in  the  bewildering 
multitude  of  facts.  Truth,  on  the  contrary,  is  an  active, 
selective  attitude  on  the  part  of  the  mind.  It  must  single 
out  characters  or  identities  from  our  concrete  changing 
world  and  thus  enable  us,  in  a  degree,  to  anticipate  its 
flow.  And  the  contents,  thus  selected,  must  be  a  genuine 
part  of  the  real  world  to  enable  us  to  dip  into  the  process 
and  predict  its  conduct.  They  are  the  warp,  which  enables 
us  to  follow  the  many-colored  woof  of  life.  As  abstractions, 
in  the  service  of  the  will,  they  seek  and  point  to  their  context. 

Nor  do  I  have  any  sympathy  with  the  dualistic  type  of 


Truth  and  Agreement  223 

realism  which  would  make  our  states  of  consciousness 
duplicates  of  the  real  object  outside.  The  assumption  of 
such  duplication  has  always  proved  fatal  to  knowledge. 
And  it  is  gratuitous  in  fact.  Sensations  are  not  copies. 
They  are  a  subjective  way  of  taking  certain  continuities 
of  our  psycho-physical  organism  with  its  objective  world. 
Neither  are  our  images,  as  such,  copies.  They  are  rela- 
tively persistent  processes  of  experience,  modified  by  in- 
tervening rearrangement.  They  become  representative 
when  they  are  the  same  in  more  than  one  context,  and, 
therefore,  when  excited  in  one  context,  suggest  another 
context  with  its  dynamic  coefficient  and  time  value.  The 
copy  theory  of  sensory  processes  can  have  meaning  only 
when  we  assume  a  social  consciousness  in  which,  as  states 
of  consciousness,  they  preexist,  as  for  example  Berkeley  sup- 
posed. But  such  a  storehouse  is  quite  superfluous.  We  can 
acknowledge  nature  as  having  a  context  of  its  own.  And 
there  is  nothing  phenomenal  about  nature,  if  we  take  it  at 
its  face  value,  as  it  appears  in  experience,  and  do  not 
attempt  to  read  our  human  purposes  into  nature. 

It  is  only  in  sharing  meaning  that  concrete  imitation  — 
the  copying  of  the  object's  own  fullness  —  can  come  in 
question.  And  here  the  truth  meaning  has  peculiar 
advantage  over  other  meanings  as  its  characters  are  al- 
ready few  and  universal.  To  share  Euclid's  geometrical 
system  is  not  only  possible,  but  comparatively  easy.  And 
when  we  do  understand  it,  we  have  Euclid's  thought. 
There  is  no  residuum  so  far  as  truth  is  concerned,  what- 
ever fringe  the  thought  may  have  otherwise  carried  in 
Euclid's  mind. 

Realism  has  always  insisted  upon  the  trans-subjective  ref- 
erence of  the  cognitive  meaning.  But  the  paradox,  often 


224  Truth  and  Reality 

pointed  out  by  realists  themselves,  that  the  object  must  be 
both  in  and  out  of  experience,  must  remain  an  absolute 
mystery  so  long  as  we  deal  with  meanings  as  subjective 
pictures,  inclosed  within  the  magic  circle  of  an  epiphe- 
nomenal  consciousness.  This  paradox  is  ignored,  not 
solved,  by  having  recourse  to  mystical  or  esthetic  theories  as 
regards  the  continuity  of  the  meaning  with  reality.  If  we, 
however,  regard  the  universe  under  the  conception  of 
plural  energetic  centers,  which  can  figure  in  various  con- 
texts, including  our  cognitive  context,  and  some  at  least  as 
having  a  meaning  of  their  own  and  capable  of  entering  into 
cognitive  relations  with  us ;  and  if,  furthermore,  we  regard 
cognitive  purposes  as  themselves  energies,  evolving  in 
complexity  with,  and  having  survival  value  through,  their 
control  of  other  energies,  such  as  the  physiological,  then 
the  paradox  is  resolved  even  if  the  practical  limitations  re- 
main. We  have  at  least  found  a  motive  for  our  ideas  seek- 
ing agreement  with  their  intended  reality,  for  successful  ad- 
justment in  the  end  depends  upon  such  agreement  And 
our  only  key  to  external  reality  is  what  we  must  take  it  as, 
in  the  realization  of  our  purposes. 

The  object,  in  any  case,  is  more  than  our  intent.  It 
belongs  to  its  own  context,  quite  independent  of  whether 
it  figures  in  our  cognitive  context  or  not.  If  the  drama  of 
reality  consisted  only  in  a  series  of  doubts,  readjustments 
and  satisfactions,  then  Plato's  subjectivistic  interpretation 
of  Protagoras  would  indeed  be  true,  that  "to  whom  a 
thing  seems  that  which  seems  is."  But  in  that  case  what 
need  could  there  be  of  readjustment  within  the  stream  of 
experience  ?  Why  should  not  the  meaning  at  any  time 
exhaust  the  situation?  Why  should  there  be  failure  or 
the  necessity  for  accommodation  to  a  larger  world  ?  Evi- 


Truth  and  Agreement  225 

dently  the  meaning  does  not  exhaust  the  reality  of  the 
object. 

This  inadequacy  of  the  internal  meaning  to  constitute 
its  own  object  can  be  shown  equally  well  on  the  level  of 
sharing  as  on  that  of  instrumental  knowledge.  Is  Ibsen's 
meaning  made  or  created  in  each  stage  of  the  process  of 
the  reader's  interpretation?  Is  not  the  object  here  some- 
thing preexisting  and  external  —  not  made  by  the  critic? 
And  must  not  the  critic's  meaning  conform  to  this  in 
order  to  be  valid  of  Ibsen's  meaning  ?  By  ideal  construc- 
tion we  try  to  reproduce  for  ourselves  the  meaning  of 
Ibsen's  play.  We  gather  data  accordingly;  but  the  truth 
we  have  first  when  our  meaning  imitates  the  other  mean- 
ing, when  it  gives  an  adequate  copy  of  the  other  mean- 
ing. In  such  a  case  the  idealists  are  quite  right  that  the 
agreement  must  be  with  truth,  an  objective  constitution 
of  truth,  and  not  merely  with  immediate  experience.  I 
cannot,  however,  see  what  agreement  with  truth  can  mean 
unless  you  assume  that  the  object  itself  is  a  truth  process. 
If  the  universe  as  a  whole  is  truth,  a  system  of  experience, 
then  of  course  all  truth  ought  to  be  a  copying  of  truth. 
But  I  do  not  think  this  has  been  proven.  Stringing 
nature  on  our  reflective  unity  does  not  make  nature  a 
reflective  unity.  There  is,  in  so  far  as  we  know,  no  truth 
or  system  in  nature.  Nature  only  furnishes  certain 
changes,  interactions  and  constancies  which  we  can  seize 
upon  and  systematize  to  suit  our  needs. 

The  immediatists  themselves  have  fretted  a  great  deal 
lately  at  their  misinterpretation  by  others.  But  why 
should  they  fret  ?  Their  critics,  realists  and  idealists  alike, 
seem  to  be  satisfied  with  their  interpretation;  and  that  is 
all  the  immediatists  ought  to  ask.  If  they  say  that  the 
Q 


226  Truth  and  Reality 

critics  ought  not  to  be  satisfied,  they  have  evidently  in- 
sisted upon  a  reality  beyond  immediacy  and  something 
besides  subjective  satisfaction  as  the  test  of  truth  —  upon 
correspondence  with  an  objective  reality. 


We  never  shall  have  a  true  theory  of  knowledge  until 
we  recognize  the  complexity  of  reality  in  its  various  stages. 
We  have  seen  that  those  who  have  made  the  knowing 
attitude  exclusively  instrumental  have  borrowed  their 
illustrations  altogether  from  the  physical  part  of  reality. 
They  talk  about  knives  and  chairs  and  chemical  formulae. 
They  are  apt  to  ignore  another  part  of  the  environment, 
which  to  a  human  being  is  at  least  equally  important  with 
the  physical,  viz.,  the  institutional.  Could  the  object  be 
treated  altogether  without  any  reference  to  any  purpose 
or  meaning  of  its  own,  then  the  instrumental  theory  would 
indeed  cover  the  field.  Were  reality  through  and  through 
reflective  or  conceptual,  on  the  other  hand;  must  we 
acknowledge  it  as  one  system  of  meanings,  then  Plato 
and  all  his  disciples  would  be  right,  that  all  knowledge  in 
the  end  must  be  expressed  in  terms  of  sharing  or  imi- 
tation —  a  copy  of  the  inner  meaning  of  the  processes  at 
which  truth  aims.  In  so  far  as  it  should  succeed  in  this,  the 
distinction  between  truth  and  reality  would  disappear; 
the  idea  would  thicken  into  being.  As  it  is,  it  is  both 
sanity  and  fair  play  to  treat  reality  as  its  nature  demands, 
instrumentally,  where  no  purpose  need  be  acknowledged ; 
sympathetically  where  the  conditions  so  demand. 

Whether  a  man  shall  be  an  idealist  or  a  materialist  is 
not  a  matter  of  consistency,  but  of  claims  which  we  must 
meet.  Where  we  must  recognize  ideals,  as  in  dealing  with 


Truth  and  Agreement  227 

the  institutional  life  of  the  race,  we  must  be  idealists. 
Where  our  ideals  have  no  inner  relevancy  to  the  processes 
with  which  we  deal  and  the  aim  is  merely  control,  we 
must  be  materialists.  Here  a  one-sided  a  priori  consis- 
tency is  as  mischievous  as  in  other  departments  of  life. 
To  institutionalize  nature  by  giving  it  reflective  life  and 
ideals  of  its  own  is  to  leave  evidence  for  fairy  tales.  To 
ignore  purposes  and  meanings,  where  we  ought  to  under- 
stand and  meet  them,  is  to  show  one's  lack  of  imagination 
and  unfitness  for  social  life.  Thus  the  truth  of  Plato,  as 
well  as  of  Kant  and  James,  is  recognized.  The  one- 
sidedness  of  the  instrumental  theory  consists  in  ignoring 
that  part  of  the  environment  which  is  institutional;  is 
itself  meanings  or  ideals.  The  one-sidedness  of  Plato 
and  his  followers  is  that  they  attempt  to  institutionalize 
nature  as  well  as  man. 

The  instrumental  theory  does  not  satisfy  the  claims  of 
the  successive  moments  of  each  individual  life  any  more 
than  it  does  the  social  claims.  It  is  not  fair  to  regard 
each  moment  of  appreciation  or  reflection  as  a  mere  in- 
strument to  another  moment.  If  each  moment  has  no 
significance  or  worth  of  its  own,  is  a  mere  instrument  for 
meeting  a  future  moment,  then  life  as  a  succession  of 
moments  can  have  no  significance.  Instrumentalism,  bare 
and  simple,  must  lead  to  bankruptcy.  Each  moment  must 
be  respected  as  end,  as  well  as  means.  Every  genuine 
moment  is  a  thing  of  beauty  and  a  joy  forever,  as  well  as 
the  parent  of  a  new  moment.  And  again,  every  false  and 
perverse  moment  is  a  tragedy  never  remedied,  as  well  as  a 
call  for  reconstruction,  if  there  is  such  a  call,  or  an  obstruc- 
tion to  further  living.  The  universe,  in  other  words,  is 
not  merely  fluid.  If  it  were,  it  would  be  nothing.  Each 


228  Truth  and  Reality 

moment  and  each  stage  of  life  is  an  individual  reality 
with  its  own  warm  and  living  meaning,  to  lose  which  is  to 
lose  all. 

The  confusion  in  recent  discussions  has  come  in  part  at 
least  from  the  failure  to  distinguish  between  truth  and 
reality.  Truth  is  our  version  of  reality.  The  geological 
ages  existed  as  characters  or  processes  of  reality  long  be- 
fore we  discovered  them,  but  the  truth  about  them  did  not 
exist  before  we  discovered  them.  It  is  nonsense  to  speak 
of  an  hypothesis,  which  is  our  meaning  or  attitude,  as  true 
previous  to  verification;  but  previous  to  verification  there 
exist  certain  conditions,  which  make  some  hypotheses  come 
true.  These  conditions,  in  most  cases,  are  not  altered  by 
our  hypothesis.  The  chemical  properties  of  gold  are  not 
altered  by  our  faith;  the  condition  of  our  nerves  may  be. 
The  "  laws  "of  nature  are  contributed  by  the  man  who  dis- 
covers them;  and  science  very  properly,  therefore,  deals 
with  the  laws  biographically,  as  Newton's  law,  Carnot's  law, 
etc.,  though  once  discovered  they  become  social  and  eternal. 
Nature  furnishes  existences,  uniformities  of  various  sorts, 
but  no  laws,  no  truth.  These  laws  or  expectancies  become 
true  when  nature  behaves  in  the  predicted  way.  This  is 
all  that  correspondence  in  regard  to  nature  means.  It  is 
not  a  one  to  one  correspondence,  as  we  only  hit  at  best  a 
few  aspects  of  reality ;  and  only  a  few  are  significant  for  us. 
Truth,  looked  at  from  the  individual  point  of  view,  becomes 
agreement  with  truth,  when  we  imitate  or  make  our  own 
truths  already  existing,  hypotheses  already  verified,  social 
truths.  Here  we  do  copy  truth,  within  the  limitations  of 
human  nature.  Truth  need  not  mean,  and  cannot  except 
to  a  small  extent  mean,  individual  verification.  An  hypothe- 
sis or  law  is  true,  if  some  one  has  really  verified  it.  Going 


Truth  and  Agreement  229 

over  it  again  in  such  a  case  does  not  make  it  true.  It  sim- 
ply relieves  our  nervousness  and  confirms  our  belief.  But 
our  belief  or  doubt  neither  verifies  nor  undoes  the  verifica- 
tion of  an  hypothesis,  though  it  may  furnish  a  motive  for 
testing  it. 

As  I  see  it,  both  the  intellectualists  and  the  anti-intellect- 
ualists  have  contributed  to  the  confusion — the  intellectual- 
ists by  tacitly,  often  unintentionally,  assuming  an  absolute 
system  of  truth  with  which  we  must  agree ;  the  anti-intellect- 
ualists  by  then*  intense  individualism  in  practically  insisting 
that  truth  is  not  truth,  unless  it  has  passed  through  their 
particular  cranium.  Of  course  a  truth  is  not  my  truth  un- 
less I  make  it  my  own  by  going  over  its  grounds,  tracing 
it  to  its  termination  in  the  intended  facts.  But  going  over 
an  hypothesis  already  verified  does  not  make  it  true  or 
valid.  This  is  a  social  fact.  Whether  I  make  it  my  own 
or  not  is  tremendously  significant  for  me,  but  is  not,  unless  I 
improve  upon  the  hypothesis,  a  contribution  to  truth.  Who- 
ever the  legatee  or  individual  producer  of  truth  may  be,  it 
is  quite  sufficient  that  truth  exist  in  one  individual  conscious- 
ness, as  his  systematic  meaning,  whatever  the  other  indi- 
viduals may  mean.  If  everybody  should  sleep  the  sleep  of 
Endymion,  there  would  be  no  truth.  If,  on  the  other  hand, 
there  is  an  omniscient,  ever  wakeful  God,  his  possession  of 
the  truth  would  give  it  all  the  validity  that  its  possession 
by  billions  could  possibly  give  it.  The  question  in  any  case 
would  be,  Does  it  terminate  in  facts  ?  Does  it,  as  judged 
by  either  past  or  present  or  future  experience,  or  all  of  them, 
meet  the  reality  we  intend  or  which  is  forced  upon  us  ? 


CHAPTER  XIII 
HUMAN  NATURE  AND  TRUTH 

IN  this  chapter  I  wish  to  discuss  three  problems:  the 
meaning  of  humanism ;  the  relation  of  motive  to  validity 
in  truth  seeking;  and  finally  certain  limitations  of  human 
nature  in  its  search  for  knowledge. 


It  is  universally  recognized  now  that  we  must  arrive  at 
truth  through  our  human  purposes,  as  the  fulfillment  and 
definition  of  human  striving.  We  can  know  nature  only  as 
it  runs  through  human  nature.1  But  we  must  distinguish 
between  coming  to  light  through  our  human  nature  and 
being  dependent  upon,  or  created  by,  human  nature. 
Human  nature  with  its  purposive  selection  determines  the 
meaning  of  the  object,  but  does  it,  as  cognitive,  determine 
the  existence  of  the  object?  Furthermore,  while  truth,  in 
the  nature  of  things,  must  be  man-made,  must  be  arrived 
at  through  human  processes  of  perception,  imagination 
and  thought,  does  that  make  truth,  once  arrived  at, 
human  ? 

In  answering  the  latter  question  first,  we  must  maintain 
that  if  truth  works,  it  is  no  longer  peculiarly  human.  The 
necessity  which  makes  our  thinking  objective  lies  not  in  us 
as  human,  but  in  the  structural  conditions  of  the  universe 

1  This  has  been  brilliantly  emphasized  by  Dr.  F.  C.  S.  Schiller,  especially  in 
his  book  "  Humanism." 

230 


Human  Nature  and  Truth  231 

which  we  must  meet.  If  animals  have  sense  perception, 
and  imagination,  as  the  higher  animals  certainly  have, 
there  is  no  reason,  so  far  as  the  evidence  goes,  to  think 
that  their  perception,  or  the  laws  of  their  association,  differ 
fundamentally  from  ours.  If  they  could  also  reason,  there 
is  no  need  for  assuming  that  their  laws  of  thought  would  be 
different  from  ours.  If  there  are  supra-human  beings  in 
the  universe,  we  must  assume  that  the  same  rules  of  logic 
and  the  same  scientific  uniformities  hold  for  them  as  for 
us.  We  cannot  think  of  them  as  having  another  law  of 
contradiction  or  another  law  of  gravitation.  Truth  is, 
strictly  speaking,  no  more  human  than  it  is  Aryan  or 
Negro.  In  any  case,  truth  is  a  relation  between  the  idea 
and  its  intended  object.  It  is  proven  true  when  the  idea 
terminates  in  its  intended  consequences. 

Another  theory,  however,  has  been  proposed  by  eminent 
thinkers,  as  regards  the  relation  of  truth  to  human  nature. 
It  has  been  held  that  human  nature  determines,  in  part  or 
altogether,  the  nature  of  the  object  which  is  known.  Ac- 
cording to  Kant,  human  nature,  on  the  one  hand,  greatly 
modifies  the  object  in  the  way  of  sensation  —  the  character 
of  the  sensation  being  due  far  more  to  human  nature  than 
to  stimuli.  On  the  other  hand,  human  nature  contributes 
the  system  of  relations  in  the  way  of  space,  time,  causality, 
etc.,  and  thus  constitutes  the  unity  of  nature.  Other 
philosophers,  while  not  consistent  in  the  working  out  of 
their  theory,  have  gone  so  far  as  to  make  the  existence  of 
the  object  dependent  altogether  upon  its  being  taken  ac- 
count of  by  human  nature.  Thus,  barring  the  tacked-on 
assumption  of  God,  in  Berkeley's  system,  the  reality  of  the 
object  is  made  to  consist  in  its  being  perceived.  Fichte 
in  a  similar  manner,  would  make  human  nature  posit  both 


232  Truth  and  Reality 

the  system  and  the  existence  of  the  datum  itself.  In 
neither  case,  however,  has  the  hypothesis  been  worked  out 
consistently.  Berkeley  has  recourse,  in  the  last  analysis, 
to  God  as  the  storehouse  of  perception,  while  Fichte  takes 
refuge  in  the  positing  by  an  absolute  ego. 

What  does  human  nature  contribute  to  nature  ?  We  must 
agree  with  Kant  that  human  nature  contributes  the  signifi- 
cant system,  or  the  cognitive  relations,  to  nature.  Nature 
has  no  significance  on  its  own  account.  In  the  cognitive 
sense,  it  is  true  that  we  make  the  unity  of  nature.  We  fur- 
nish the  conventional  units,  by  means  of  which  we  take  stock 
of  nature's  energies.  Our  yardsticks  are  our  measures.  Our 
mathematical  equations  and  our  syllogisms  are  our  human 
contributions.  They  are  our  tools  for  the  description  of 
our  perceptions.  They  must  be  justified  by  their  conven- 
ience, as  such  human  tools.  Nature  knows  them  not. 
The  selecting  of  certain  aspects,  the  abstracting  of  these 
from  their  concrete  setting,  our  construction  of  hypotheses 
—  these  are  human  activities,  the  result  of  the  human  in- 
terest, which  we  bring.  But  while  we  admit  that  human 
nature  is  responsible  for  our  cognitive  system  of  nature,  we 
cannot  on  that  account  hold  that  human  nature  unifies  or  con- 
nects arbitrarily.  It  does  not  constitute  the  existential  con- 
nections of  nature.  Our  human  unification  must  in  the 
last  analysis  tally  with  the  coexistences,  sequences  and 
interconnections  in  nature.  Our  conventional  measures 
of  distance,  or  of  time,  or  of  weight,  do  not  constitute  the 
objects  with  which  they  deal  —  the  existential  relations  of 
distance,  or  time,  or  weight.  Our  equations  must  be  ca- 
pable of  dipping  into  the  real  stream  of  concrete  experience 
in  order  to  be  valid.  The  coexistences  and  uniformities 
of  nature  are  not  made  by  our  perceiving  them,  though 


Human  Nature  and  Truth  233 

they  become  significant  for  us,  when  they  thus  become 
conscious.  Nor  must  we  suppose  that  stringing  the  facts 
on  the  unity  of  our  consciousness  makes  nature  itself  an 
experiential  unity.  Whether  nature  is  such  or  not  must  be 
determined  with  reference  to  the  demands  of  our  conduct 
towards  nature.  What  human  experience  contributes  is 
significance.  It  does  not  contribute  existence. 

Existentially,  nature  must  be  acknowledged  as  being  what 
we  must  take  it  as,  in  varying  contexts.  Of  these  contexts 
human  nature  is  one.  Through  its  organic  differentiation, 
human  nature,  no  doubt,  conditions  the  existence  of  some 
qualities,  such  as  tone  and  color.  Other  qualities,  again,  such 
as  form,  weight,  size,  temperature  and  resistance  must  be 
taken  as  existing  in  other  contexts  besides  the  organic  con- 
text. If  we  take  relations,  again,  here,  too,  it  holds  that 
some  relations,  such  as  similarity  and  difference,  fitness,  con- 
sistency and  proportion,  must  be  regarded  as  relations  to 
human  nature,  while  again  other  relations,  such  as  distance 
and  causality,  must  be  taken  to  exist  independently  of  human 
nature.  As  values  mean  satisfaction  and  are  conditioned 
upon  the  realization  of  the  will,  they  cannot  exist  independ- 
ently of  conscious,  willing  beings.  But,  in  any  case,  human 
nature  as  cognitive  does  not  make  the  qualities,  relations,  or 
values.  It  only  makes  them  significant  for  us.  Even  our 
own  past  meanings  and  the  meanings  of  others  must  be 
taken  as  existing  independently  of  the  cognitive  moment. 

Human  experience,  moreover,  has  its  own  laws  of  con- 
nection, its  own  history,  quite  independent  of  the  object  of 
which  it  takes  account.  While  the  condition  for  our  tak- 
ing account  of  causality  is  doubtless,  as  Hume  pointed  out, 
the  law  of  habit,  the  causal  connections  need  not,  there- 
fore, be  conceived  as  subjective  habit.  Our  processes  of 


234  Truth  and  Reality 

becoming  conscious  of  nature  may  have  nothing  to  do  with 
the  behavior  of  the  facts  which  we  intend.  Thus,  while 
our  synthesis  of  the  properties  of  the  chemical  elements,  of 
the  parts  of  a  geometrical  system,  takes  place  in  time  and 
may  require  ages  of  successive  experiences,  the  chemical 
elements  and  Euclidian  geometry  may  remain  constant. 
While  our  meanings  change,  they  may  refer  to  relatively 
stable  qualities,  relations  and  values,  on  the  part  of  the 
object.  Again,  while  our  meanings  may  remain  compar- 
atively constant,  they  may  refer  to  a  world  of  infinitesimal 
succession  as  regards  their  object. 

Our  ideals,  no  more  than  our  facts,  can  be  regarded  as 
the  mere  functions  of  human  nature.  On  the  contrary, 
human  nature  in  its  striving  must  own  these  ideals  as 
obligations  or  limits.  This  is  implied  in  every  endeavor 
for  truth,  right  or  beauty.  The  world  of  experience,  as 
we  find  it,  must  be  criticized,  selected  and  reconstructed 
in  order  to  fulfill  our  ideal  demands.  These,  therefore, 
must  be  regarded  as  part  of  the  objective  constitution  of 
our  world. 

II 

We  must  distinguish,  in  the  second  place,  between  the  mo- 
tive for  seeking  the  truth  and  the  test  of  truth  itself.  Con- 
siderable confusion  has  arisen  from  the  failure  to  make  this 
distinction.  The  two  need  not  be  identical.  The  motive 
for  truth  is  always  to  be  found  in  our  affective-volitional 
nature.  The  test  of  truth  may  be  quite  independent  of  our 
feelings  and  desires.  It  would  at  least  be  as  true  to  say 
that  our  affective-volitional  nature  is  the  bane  of  truth,  as  to 
say  that  it  makes  the  idea  true.  For  our  will-to-believe  often 
makes  us  incapable  of  seeing  the  objective  agreements  and 


Human  Nature  and  Truth  235 

blinds  us  to  the  real  facts.  Hatred  and  love  make  it  alike 
difficult  to  estimate  human  motives  for  what  they  are.  Only 
the  pure  in  heart  can  see.  The  only  way  in  which  our  affec- 
tive-volitional nature  can  influence  the  agreement  of  an 
idea  with  its  object  is  in  those  cases  in  which  our  will  alters 
the  situation;  where  our  will-to-believe  is  an  important  con- 
dition in  the  events  coming  to  pass.  It  is  reported  of 
Charles  Lamb  that  he  refused  to  admit  that  two  and 
two  make  four  until  informed  what  use  was  going  to  be 
made  of  it.  But  the  relation  involved  in  the  equation,  any 
one  must  see,  is  quite  independent  of  any  ulterior  motive. 
The  motive  of  Mme.  Curie  for  investigating  radio-active 
substances  may  have  been  loyalty  to  her  husband,  but  this 
does  not  affect  the  truth  of  her  investigations.  The 
validity  of  Hobbes's  contract  theory  does  not  suffer  from 
his  motive  to  defend  the  divine  right  of  kings.  The  dis- 
covery by  Columbus  of  a  new  continent  is  not  affected  by 
his  search  for  a  passage  to  the  Indies. 

On  the  other  hand,  we  must  keep  in  mind  that  no  truth 
is  possible  without  interest  —  without  the  fringe  of  the 
associative  context  with  its  affective  tone.  We  cannot 
have  the  seeking  for  truth  in  a  merely  neutral  way.  It 
presupposes  more  than  a  tabula  rasa.  The  impartial 
spectator,  in  the  case  of  truth-seeking,  is  not  a  spectator 
void  of  interest,  but  a  spectator  with  an  objective  interest 
in  the  situation.  Truth  must  always  be  the  fulfillment  of 
will,  whether  this  will  be  divine  curiosity  or  the  will  to 
know  for  some  practical  end  ;  and  it  is  most  effective  when 
we  have  a  passionate  purpose,  provided,  of  course,  that 
purpose  is  to  discover  the  real  agreement  involved,  and  not 
to  pervert  the  truth  relation. 

Truth  is  not  the  whole  of  the  mental  situation.     It  is 


236  Truth  and  Reality 

only  an  abstract  part  of  it  It  does  not  have  to  do  with  its 
indoors  and  out-of-doors,  its  likes  and  dislikes,  its  ambition 
or  failure,  with  the  peculiar  imagery,  whether  visual  or 
some  other  type ;  but  with  the  pointing  or  leading  of  an 
idea  to  a  certain  object,  just  as  money  may  be  of  paper  or 
silver  or  gold,  may  be  carried  in  all  sorts  of  ways,  handed 
over  under  all  sorts  of  emotional  circumstances,  but  is 
valued  because  it  passes. 

What,  then,  constitutes  the  validity  of  truth  ?  We  must 
not,  as  has  sometimes  been  done,  confuse  the  meaning  of  a 
proposition  and  its  validity.  We  may  understand  the 
meaning,  clearly  and  distinctly,  of  Thales'  hypothesis,  that 
all  is  water,  but  that  does  not  have  anything  to  do  with  the 
validity  of  the  proposition.  Truth,  as  pragmatism  has  em- 
phasized, must  be  tested  by  its  termination  in  the  in- 
tended facts.  If  we  define  truth  as  agreement  with  reality, 
this  means  in  the  last  analysis,  not  agreement  with  reality 
in  general,  but  with  the  experiences  connected  with 
its  intended  object  The  intent  must  terminate  in  its 
selected  facts.  An  idea  which  cannot  be  thus  verified  in 
the  ongoing  of  experience,  either  by  becoming  directly 
continuous  with  our  perception  or  by  indirectly  making 
such  a  difference,  either  to  the  facts  that  can  be  perceived 
or  to  our  emotional-volitional  nature,  that  we  must  assume 
it  —  such  an  idea  lies  outside  of  the  domain  of  truth.  We 
cannot  say  that  truth  itself  consists  in  its  consequences, 
because  truth  involves  constructive  imagination,  with  its 
formal  demands,  as  well  as  data.  But  we  may  say  that  the 
test  or  evidence  of  truth  consists  in  consequences,  in  our 
ability  to  take  our  objects  in  actual  procedure  as  pictured 
by  our  idea. 

Some  recent  writers  have  used  two  criteria  in  determin- 


Human  Nature  and  Truth  237 

ing  truth  —  that  of  termination  in  facts,  or  the  scientific 
criterion  just  given,  and  that  of  the  good,  or  the  practical 
criterion.  In  either  case,  the  truth  is  held  to  work.  Ac- 
cording to  the  optimism  of  these  philosophers,  the  two 
coincide  —  that  which  agrees  with  facts  is  always  the  good 
and  vice  versa.  No  doubt,  in  the  long  run,  the  two  coin- 
cide, but  not  necessarily  in  any  finite  span ;  and  correspond- 
ence in  the  long  run  cannot  be  regarded  as  an  adequate 
test  of  truth.  In  some  fields  of  human  experience,  how- 
ever, as  in  the  case  of  ethical,  esthetic  and  religious  reali- 
ties, 'the  only  criterion  we  can  use  is  that  of  satisfaction, 
of  the  good.  The  consequences  which  we  must  use  as  tests 
in  the  case  of  religious  reality,  as  in  the  case  of  all  spiritual 
realities  including  social  unities,  cannot  be  consequences 
of  immediate  perception,  but  must  be  practical  conse- 
quences —  consequences  as  regards  the  coherency  and 
effectiveness  of  conduct,  the  appreciation  of  beauty,  etc. 
If  we  must  act  as  if  such  realities  exist,  then  we  must  also 
regard  them  as  real.  But  truth,  in  any  case,  whether  taken 
in  its  strict  scientific  sense,  or  in  the  more  practical  and 
proximate  sense  of  religion,  is  always  a  plan  of  procedure. 
The  supra-human  world,  as  well  as  the  infra-human,  must 
be  judged  by  what  we  must  take  it  as,  in  our  developing 
experience.  The  concept,  in  either  case,  must  lead  to 
definite  conduct  toward  the  intended  reality;  and  the  con- 
duct must  bring  the  expected  fruits. 

While  we  must  distinguish  between  the  affective-voli- 
tional motive  and  the  conditions  which  truth  must  meet ; 
while  our  feelings  and  desires  do  not,  except  where  they 
alter  reality,  make  ideas  true,  we  must  not  forget  the  funda- 
mental unity  of  human  nature.  We  have  seen  that  it  is 
not  necessary  that  truth  should  be  cold  and  unemotional. 


238  Truth  and  Reality 

It  may,  and  when  actively  pursued  does,  glow  like  the 
Holy  Grail.  The  truth  seeker  may  have  the  religious 
enthusiasm  of  a  Plato  or  a  Spinoza.  The  truth  process 
itself  must  be  regarded  as  a  satisfaction  of  a  fundamental 
demand  of  human  nature,  and,  as  such,  must  be  regarded 
as  a  good.  It  was'Tlato  who  said,  "  the  discovery  of  truth  is 
a  common  good."  J  It  is  also  true,  as  Plato  pointed  out, 
that  the  search  for  truth  is  a  noble  search,  and  requires  a 
noble  nature.  Both  Plato  and  Lotze  have  likewise  recog- 
nized the  esthetic  value  of  truth  itself,  with  its  simplicity 
and  unity.  Human  nature  in  its  realization  can  be  seen 
to  be  fundamentally  one,  and  the  realization  of  the  true 
must  be  seen  to  be  fundamentally  bound  up  with  the  right 
and  the  beautiful,  and  all  to  be  species  of  the  good ;  yet 
this  does  not  prevent  us  from  recognizing  certain  differen- 
tia in  this  ultimate  good.  The  good  always  means  proper 
functioning  on  the  part  of  human  nature  in  its  various 
relations,  the  harmonious  activity  of  all  its  activities  or 
capacities,  fluency  of  life,  consistency  of  transitions.  Now 
this  is  true  of  the  right  and  the  beautiful,  as  it  is  of  the 
true.  The  right  means  fluency  of  functioning,  as  regards 
human  individuals  in  their  institutional  relations,  the  pro- 
portional equalization  of  claims.  The  beautiful  means  the 
harmonious  and  complete  expression  of  our  esthetic  de- 
mands, the  feeling  of  fitness  and  support  as  regards  the 
various  parts  of  the  esthetic  object.  Truth  means  the 
fluent  termination  of  the  clear  and  distinct  idea  in  its  in- 
tended facts.  In  the  equilibrated  life  of  the  individual  as 
a  whole,  all  human  nature  —  cognitive,  volitional  and  emo- 
tional —  must  function  with  ease  and  fluency  of  transition, 
without  conflict  of  the  true  with  the  beautiful  or  useful, 

1  Plato,  "  Gorgias,"  §  505. 


Human  Nature  and  Truth  239 

or  the  ethically  good.  They  are,  nevertheless,  specific 
forms  of  the  good  ;  and,  in  our  imperfect  finite  develop- 
ment', there  may  be  provisional  conflict. 

Ill 

While  we  must  know  through  human  nature  — by  means 
of  its  interests  and  tools,  it  has  long  been  pointed  out  that 
human  nature  works  under  certain  limitations.  In  criticiz- 
ing human  nature,  however,  we  must  be  fair.  We  cannot, 
for  example,  regard  it  as  a  limitation  that  we  must  know 
by  means  of  human  nature  as  such.  We  cannot  contrast 
the  process  of  human  knowledge  with  another  mode  of 
knowing,  to  the  disadvantage  of  the  former,  for  it  must  be 
evident  on  reflection  that  we  have  no  other  mode  of  know- 
ing excepting  human  nature,  and  that  any  supposed 
supra-human  method  of  consciousness  must  itself  be  an 
abstraction  from  the  method  of  knowing  as  we  find  it  in 
our  own  experience.  The  intuitional  mode  of  knowing, 
which  has  sometimes  been  attributed  to  a  superior  being, 
is,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  a  genuine  method  of  experience  in 
ourselves.  It  is  a  short  cut  for  long  processes  of  associa- 
tion and  thinking  of  which  the  immediate  intuition  is  the 
accumulated  meaning. 

Nor  can  we  criticize  our  human  knowledge,  because  we 
are  a  part  as  knowers  of  a  context  of  history,  social  as  well 
as  individual.  There  would  be  no  knowledge  at  all  unless 
we  had  the  advantage  of  the  cumulative  experience  of  the 
race  as  assimilated  in  our  own  learning  process.  All  our 
orientation  to  reality  must  be  with  reference  to  such  a 
social  context.  We  must  imitate  the  social  heritage  of  the 
past,  before  we  can  make  any  intelligent  contribution  of 
our  own.  Nor  can  we  start  on  our  journey  of  discovery 


240  Truth  and  Reality 

without  such  instruments  as  concepts  or  hypotheses  to 
steer  our  course.  Knowledge  cannot  be  a  mere  passive 
accumulation  of  impressions.  It  must  be  an  active  sorting 
on  the  basis  of  certain  suggestions  that  are  derived  from 
past  experience,  individual  and  social.  All  we  can  demand 
is  a  willingness  to  revise  our  suggestions  in  accordance 
with  the  demands  of  our  procedure. 

We  cannot,  however,  as  some  have  recently  maintained, 
rid  ourselves,  at  one  stroke,  of  all  the  problems  involved 
in  the  relation  of  the  object  to  human  nature  by  assuming 
that  consciousness  is  diaphanous.  It  is  quite  true 
that  consciousness  in  the  abstract,  i.e.,  as  the  bare  con- 
dition of  awareness,  does  not  alter  the  facts  or  their 
relations.  But  the  process  of  knowing  involves  more 
than  the  bare  fact  of  awareness.  It  involves,  funda- 
mentally, the  problem  of  interest.  And  it  is  in  the 
nature  of  interest  that  we  find  both  the  conditions  for 
knowledge  and  the  limitations  of  knowledge.  We  have 
already  discussed  the  former.  We  must  now  say  a  few 
words  about  the  latter. 

There  are  first  of  all  certain  limitations  due  to  our  bio- 
logical heritage.  It  was  pointed  out  as  early  as  Locke, 
that  the  sense  qualities,  furnished  by  the  end  organs  of  our 
organism,  are  by  no  means  exhaustive  of  the  possible  range 
of  sense  qualities.  Evolution  has  been  interested  primarily 
in  furnishing  certain  practical  guides  to  conduct.  It  has 
had  no  care  for  completeness  of  such  sensory  reactions. 
The  program  of  human  interest  must  therefore  be  worked 
out  within  the  limitations  furnished  by  our  sense  instru- 
ments, and  such  artificial  means  as  we  have  found  for  the 
extension  of  these  in  the  way  of  telescopes,  microscopes 
and  other  instruments. 


Human  Nature  and  Truth  241 

Coming  to  the  problem  proper  of  the  nature  of  interest, 
we  must  remember  that  human  nature  is  fundament- 
ally instinctive  and  impulsive,  and  that  our  interest  is 
throughout  determined  by  this  instinctive  mental  constitu- 
tion. There  are,  in  the  first  place,  probably  some  racial  dif- 
ferences due  to  this  instinctive  heritage.  It  is  true  that  it  is 
extremely  difficult  to  make  out  just  how  much  must  be  at- 
tributed to  fundamental  race  difference.  We  know  now 
that  a  great  deal  which  we  once  attributed  to  race  difference 
can  be  accounted  for  as  due  to  social  suggestion  and  imita- 
tion. Not  only  is  this  true  of  certain  mental  characteristics, 
in  the  way  of  customs  and  traditions,  but  it  is  true  also  of 
certain  physiological  characteristics,  such  as  peculiar  ges- 
tures, bearing,  mien,  and  facial  characteristics.  The  pecul- 
iar gestures  of  the  Hebrews  and  Italiansare  duemerely  to  the 
imitation  of  tradition,  and  fail  to  stick  in  a  new  social  environ- 
ment. Our  so-called  race  problems  are  largely  due  to  the 
blindness  of  social  prejudices.  The  southern  baby  mani- 
fests no  antipathy  to  its  colored  "  mammy."  The  fashion- 
able lady  is  not  troubled  by  the  supposed  race  odor  of  her 
colored  coachman.  Some  of  the  finest  loyalties  I  have 
known  have  been  between  Jews  and  Anglo-Saxons.  For 
all  that,  however,  I  believe  that  there  is  a  fundamental  dif- 
ference in  genius,  due  to  difference  in  race.  It  is  no  his- 
toric accident,  I  think,  that  the  Hebrews  have  given  us  the 
most  fundamental  story  of  religious  insight  and  devotion ; 
that  the  Greeks  have  given  us  a  new  appreciation  of  art 
and  science ;  that  the  Hindoos  have  contributed  an  inter- 
esting type  of  pessimistic  mysticism  ;  that  the  negroes  have 
given  us  the  characteristic  southern  folk  songs.  In  the 
long  run,  this  instinctive  genius  of  the  race  dictates  its 
type  of  contribution  to  social  institutions ;  constitutes  the 


242  Truth  and  Reality 

race  or  nation  a  chosen  people ;  conditions  the  peculiar 
gift  which  a  people  brings  to  the  world's  civilization. 

This  race  genius  constitutes  necessarily  a  limitation  of 
appreciation.  The  Greeks  could  not  appreciate  the  sense 
of  holiness  of  the  Jew.  The  Jew  in  turn  could  not  enter 
into  the  free  world  of  Greek  creativeness  in  science  and  art. 
Even  when  we  rise  above  mere  brutal  prejudice,  such  as 
the  ants  probably  feel  when  irritated  by  the  odor  of  another 
species ;  even  on  the  fair  ground  of  competition  and  sympathy, 
race  differences,  while  they  exist,  probably  constitute  certain 
limitations  in  the]way  of  human  blindness.  They  require  an 
education  in  tolerance  and  appreciation.  While  again  a 
large  number  of  human  beings  adopt  Christianity,  each  race 
has  made  it  over  and  must  translate  it  in  terms  of  its  own 
genius.  The  reason  for  the  permanency  of  the  geographical 
line  between  protestantism  and  Catholicism  in  Europe  lies 
in  part  in  temperament  and  mental  constitution  due  to 
race. 

When  we  pass  from  the  race  to  the  individual,  through 
whom,  in  the  last  analysis,  the  various  streams  of  energy 
must  pass  in  order  to  be  known,  we  must  bear  in  mind  that 
the  individual  is  no  bare  logic  machine  for  grinding  out 
certain  mechanical  results,  but  that  he  is  fundamentally 
will,  a  bundle  of  tendencies  and  emotions.  However  we 
may  conceive  of  individual  beginnings,  whether  individual 
consciousness  is  a  migrating  soul  through  the  ages,  or  a 
creative  act  on  the  part  of  the  world  process,  as  we  find  him 
at  any  rate,  he  is  a  unique  center  of  energy,  with  important 
emotional  and  temperamental  characteristics.  William 
James,  in  a  flash  of  genius,  divided  human  beings  tempera- 
mentally into  the  tough-minded  and  the  tender-minded,  with 
their  variations.  It  is  true  that  our  fundamental  ways  of 


Human  Nature  and  Truth  243 

looking  at  truth,  the  basic  warp  of  our  philosophic  systems, 
is  constituted  in  no  small  part  by  such  temperamental  dif- 
ferences. There  will  always  be  the  great  idealistic  stream 
of  tendency,  with  its  emphasis  upon  unities  and  esthetic 
completeness,  on  the  one  hand,  and  the  realistic  stream, 
with  its  emphasis  on  facts  and  fundamental  cleavages  on 
the  other.  This  can  be  seen,  not  only  in  philosophy  proper, 
with  its  interest  in  the  wholeness  of  things,  but  in  the  vari- 
ous sciences  as  well,  with  their  hypotheses.  The  type  of 
ideal  construction  differs  fundamentally  between  those  who 
would  translate  experience  into  an  ideal  scheme  like  the  vor- 
tex theory,  and  the  modest  effort  merely  to  tabulate  and  pre- 
dict the  facts  within  particular  provinces  of  experience. 
And  between  the  speculative  and  the  matter-of-fact  types  of 
mind,  there  will  always  be  more  or  less  suspicion  and  lack 
of  understanding. 

Not  only  does  temperament  affect  our  view  of  the  syn- 
thesis of  facts,  but  it  affects  as  well  our  emotional  attitude 
towards  them.  Thus  pessimism  and  optimism,  as  attitudes 
towards  the  value  of  life,  seem  to  be  ineradicable  distinctions 
in  the  constitution  of  human  beings,  and  practically  not 
affected  by  the  vicissitudes  of  fortune.  The  optimistic 
temperament  will  paint  new  heavens  and  a  new  earth,  in 
times  of  the  greatest  social  stress  and  misfortune,  while  the 
pessimistic  temperament  will  invent  a  world-philosophy  of 
despair  and  nihilism  in  ages  of  greatest  prosperity  and 
outward  success.  To  the  temperamental  pessimist,  the 
optimist  seems  at  best  superficial  and  inane.  To  the 
temperamental  optimist,  the  pessimist  seems  a  melancholiac. 
Understanding  under  such  extreme  temperamental  condi- 
tions is  out  of  the  question.  Temperament,  therefore, 
enters  in  as  a  fundamantal  presupposition  in  the  selection 


244  Truth  and  Reality 

and  emphasis  of  our  facts  and  thus  conditions  and  limits 
the  world  of  the  understanding. 

No  less  radical  is  the  cleavage  between  the  once  born 
and  the  twice  born,  the  healthy  minded  and  the  regenerate 
type  of  emotional  consciousness.  To  the  twice  born  the 
once  born  seem  to  have  missed  the  fundamental  significance 
of  life.  The  twice  born  looks  back  upon  his  own  past  self, 
with  its  activities  and  ideals,  its  glowing  values,  and  counts 
it  less  than  nothing  —  a  mere  illusion  as  compared  with 
the  real  world  which  he  has  now  grasped.  Thus  Paul 
looks  back  upon  his  ardent  career  as  a  disciple  of  Gamaliel ; 
and  Tolstoy  upon  the  creative  activity  which  made  him 
famous.  The  once  born,  on  the  other  hand,  in  the  even, 
healthy-minded  tenor  of  his  ways,  fails  to  sympathize  with 
the  dualism  of  the  twice  born,  and  counts  it  at  best  emotional 
idiosyncrasy.  The  kingdom  not  of  this  world  is  not  for 
him. 

If  there  is  a  wide  diversity  and  corresponding  blindness 
as  regards  the  temperamental  and  emotional  nature  of 
individuals,  there  is  no  less  a  difference  in  the  intellectual 
range  of  interest,  outside  of  which  the  individual  is  color- 
blind. The  fool  cannot  sympathize  with  the  world  in 
which  Socrates  finds  his  absorbing  enjoyment,  and  Socrates 
can  see  but  little  value  in  the  circumscribed  uncritical 
universe  of  the  fool.  Genius  will  always  present  a  problem 
to  the  average  mind.  Its  spontaneity  and  surprises,  its 
phenomenal  absorption  in  the  task  at  hand,  its  disregard 
of  custom  and  convention,  will  always  seem  a  species  of 
insanity,  if  not  an  object  for  intolerant  persecution,  on  the 
part  of  conventional  society. 

The  sort  of  universe  that  shall  be  ours,  therefore,  as 
regards  truth  and  appreciation,  right  and  beauty,  whether 


Human  Nature  and  Truth  245 

of  high  or  low  grade,  of  what  unique  quality,  is  determined 
for  us  by  our  instinctive  heritage.  Education  may  fail  to 
furnish  the  proper  stimuli  It  may  play  them  wrongly, 
but  it  cannot  alter  the  fundamental  quality  of  temperament 
and  insight.  Then,  too,  our  preferences  and  capacities 
play  strangely  into  the  hands  of  our  limitations.  Our  capacity 
for  lyric  sweetness  unfits  us  for  appreciating  the  searching 
grandeur  of  tragedy ;  our  fondness  for  the  babbling  brook 
may  make  us  deaf  to  the  music  of  the  sea.  Our  Puritani- 
cal strenuous  mood  blinds  us  to  the  beauty  of  art  and  play. 
Our  creative  capacity  unfits  us  for  the  routine  of  practical 
life,  with  its  joys  of  successful  achievement.  An  absolutely 
catholic  nature  tuned  to  the  whole  scale  of  the  universe,  its 
dur  and  moll,  its  tragedy  and  comedy,  its  Raphaels  and 
Millets,  is  an  ideal  limit,  not  a  historic  fact.  For  the  mass 
of  us,  at  least,  the  universe  is  illumined  only  in  part. 

Not  only  are  we  limited  by  our  instinctive  heritage,  as 
regards  our  blindness  and  insight,  we  are  also  limited  by 
the  fact  that  we  are  a  part  of  an  historic  context,  individual 
and  social.  Looking  at  life  from  the  individual  point  of 
view,  we  find  it  difficult  to  understand  the  significance  of 
the  other  stages  of  development.  The  boy  romances 
about  the  man  and  his  pursuits.  To  him  they  become 
mirages,  vastly  enlarged  and  colored  by  the  angle  of 
perspective.  The  man  finds  it  equally  difficult  to  enter 
into  the  world  of  the  child  with  its  toys,  its  playful  moods 
and  its  circumscribed  point  of  view. 

Again,  from  the  point  of  view  of  social  history,  we  must 
recognize  that  we  are  a  part  of  a  social  context  of  thought 
and  appreciation,  a  context  suffused  with  feeling  and  made 
conservative  by  force  of  habit.  Before  we  can  reflect  we 
imitate  the  social  heritage  in  the  way  of  axioms  and 


246  Truth  and  Reality 

traditions,  and  even  the  greatest  genius  can  rise  above 
these  and  by  means  of  these,  only  to  a  limited  degree. 
That  we  accept  the  Copernican  theory,  Darwinian  Evolu- 
tion, international  arbitration,  is  due  largely  to  a  system  of 
beliefs  into  which  we  are  bred,  and  it  is  difficult  for  us  to 
sympathize  with  the  more  primitive  viewpoints  that  seemed 
equally  convincing  to  a  previous  age.  The  axioms  which 
we  now  accept  will  probably  in  turn  seem  equally  relative 
and  unconvincing  to  a  future  age;  but  we  cannot  make 
that  real  to  ourselves  now. 

This  brings  me  to  another  difficulty,  and  that  is  the 
limitation  as  regards  time  or  the  creative  nature  of  the 
universe.  Reality,  so  far  as  human  history  is  concerned, 
cannot  be  regarded  as  complete  in  one  edition.  No  chains 
of  Parmenides  have  succeeded  in  holding  the  universe 
stable  as  regards  its  significance.  We  cannot  read  off, 
except  merely  hypothetically,  the  future  of  the  race.  And 
we  do  this  only  by  eliminating  the  growth  element  and 
emphasizing  constancies.  Were  time  an  infinite  series,  then, 
once  knowing  the  law  of  the  series,  we  should  also  know 
the  limiting  term  and  the  sum  of  the  series.  We  should 
know  the  nature  of  the  whole  as  thoroughly  as  though  we 
had  completed  all  of  the  steps.  But  our  serial  construction 
of  time  is  but  a  phenomenal  tool  for  dealing  with  the  real 
time  process.  The  end  cannot  be  read  off  from  the  begin- 
ning. We  must  wait  for  the  new  meanings,  the  gift  of  the 
future.  In  the  meantime  we  live  by  faith.  We  adjust  our- 
selves as  best  we  can,  on  the  basis  of  such  identities  as 
experience  presents,  amidst  its  transient  and  changing 
values.  We  must  act  upon  the  light  as  we  see  the  light. 
The  only  thing  eternal  about  our  attitude  is  the  willingness 
to  see  new  light  —  the  tolerance  and  f  airmindedness  which 


Human  Nature  and  Truth  247 

acknowledges  that  truth  is  not  a  finite  quantity  and  cannot 
be  foreclosed.  For  the  survival  of  our  individual  insights, 
we  depend  upon  a  constitution  larger  than  our  experience. 
If  truth  has  its  roots  in  certain  instinctive  demands  of  our 
nature,  which  set  the  program  of  the  truth  process,  its 
survival  conditions  lie  beyond  ourselves  in  the  historic  ex- 
perience of  the  race  with  its  ideal  direction.  What  shall 
have  worth  or  meaning  in  the  process  cannot  be  determined 
by  either  the  individual  or  social  meaning  of  this  cross- 
section  of  the  historic  stream.  Our  purposes  shall  survive, 
if  they  prove  significant  in  the  ultimate  ongoing  of 
experience  and  meet  its  ideal  demands.  Whether  or  not 
they  do  so,  only  the  future  can  decide. 


PART   IV 
TRUTH   AND   ITS   OBJECT 


CHAPTER   XIV 
PRAGMATIC  REALISM 

IN  the  following  chapter  I  wish  to  discuss  three  points : 
the  definition  of  realism ;  some  objections  against  realism ; 
and  some  consequences  of  pragmatic  realism. 


There  has  been  a  great  deal  of  confusion  in  regard  to 
terms  in  recent  discussion.  It  may  be  well,  therefore,  to 
define,  at  the  outset,  what  we  mean  by  realism.  A  number 
of  writers  have  called  themselves  realists  and  proposed  to 
champion  realism,  when  they  are  really  indistinguishable 
from  idealists.  Here,  at  least,  the  Leibnizian  law  of  indis- 
cernibles  ought  to  hold.  If  the  terms  realism  and  idealism 
are  retained  at  all,  they  ought  to  stand  for  different  con- 
cepts. Leaving  out  all  reference  to  the  metaphysical 
stuff  for  the  time  being,  realism  means  the  reference  to  an 
object  existing  beyond  the  apperceptive  unity  of  momentary 
individual  consciousness,  and  that  the  object  can  make  a 
difference  to  this  consciousness  so  as  to  be  known.  The 
object,  in  other  words,  is  dependent  upon  the  cognitive 
moment,  not  for  its  existence,  but  for  its  significance. 
Idealism,  on  the  other  hand,  would  hold  that  there  is 
strictly  only  one  unity  of  consciousness  and  that  existence 
is  a  function  of  being  part  of  a  significant  cognitive  system. 
Thought  is  so  wedded  to  things  that  things  cannot  exist 
without  being  thought.  This  assumption  on  the  part  of 

251 


252  Truth  and  Reality 

idealism  may  be  veiled  under  various  terms,  such  as 
appearance  and  reality,  the  finite  and  the  infinite,  the  in- 
complete purpose  and  the  completely  fulfilled  purpose; 
but  in  the  various  forms  of  expression  the  assumption 
remains  that  all  the  facts  are  ultimately  and  really  strung 
on  one  unity  of  thought. 

Realism  is  an  epistemological  attitude  and  has  to  do 
with  the  relation  of  the  cognitive  meaning  to  its  object. 
As  regards  stuff,  it  may  be  materialistic,  spiritualistic, 
dualistic  or  pluralistic.  As  regards  connection  it  may 
hold  the  mechanical  interpretation  concerning  the  relation 
of  parts ;  or  it  may  hold  the  teleological  point  of  view ;  or 
partly  one,  partly  the  other,  which  is  the  position  common- 
sense  realism  takes.  As  regards  the  numerical  distinct- 
ness of  the  universe,  it  may  be  monistic,  holding  the  uni- 
verse to  be  one  individual  with  only  apparent  diversity  in 
space  and  time ;  or  it  may  be  frankly  pluralistic,  holding  to 
the  numerical  diversity  and  distinctness  of  individuals. 
As  realism,  therefore,  is  pledged  to  no  brand  of  meta- 
physics, no  odium  need  attach  to  it  so  far  as  metaphysics 
is  concerned. 

Realism,  as  I  understand  it,  does  not  assume  that  there 
can  exist  isolated  or  independent  individuals  of  such  a  kind 
as  to  make  no  difference  to  other  individuals.  No  indi- 
vidual has  any  properties,  chemical  any  more  than  psycho- 
logical, by  itself.  Qualities  are  reactions  or  expectancies 
within  determinate  contexts.  An  isolated  individual  can- 
not even  be  zero,  as  zero  must  be  part  of  a  logical  context 
at  least.  The  hypothesis  of  independent  reals  is  founded 
either  on  contradictory  or  on  purely  hypothetical  conditions. 
Kant's  things-in-themselves  are  instances  of  the  latter 
kind.  These  cannot  exist  for  experience  or  in  relation  to 


Pragmatic  Realism  253 

things  as  known.  Yet  they  are  supposed  to  be  possible 
for  an  intuition  entirely  different  from  ours.  Leibniz  has 
recourse  in  the  last  analysis  to  an  emanation  theory  and 
preestablished  harmony,  which  contradict  his  assumed 
independence.  Cognitively  independent  his  monads  could 
not  be  in  any  case,  since  by  implication  they  are  aware  of 
each  other. 

Realism  does  not  deny  that  objects  to  be  known  must 
make  a  difference  to  reflective  experience;  that  they  are 
capable  of  being  taken  in  a  cognitive  context.  To  deny 
this,  within  the  universe  of  truth,  would  be  self-contra- 
dictory. What  realism  insists  is  that  objects  can  also 
exist  and  must  exist  in  a  context  of  their  own,  whether 
past  or  present  —  independent  of  the  cognitive  subject; 
that  they  can  make  differences  within  non-cognitive  con- 
texts, independent  of  the  cognitive  experience,  of  which 
the  latter  a  posteriori  must  take  account.  Thus  the  wood 
in  the  grate  burns,  even  though  we  are  not  taking  account 
of  it;  the  seed  grows  when  we  are  asleep,  through 
properties  involved  in  its  chemical  context.  Even  our 
own  meanings  grow  without  our  being  reflectively  aware  of 
their  change. 

As  our  own  cognitive  meanings  are  necessarily  finite, 
and  any  other  type  of  knowing  is  necessarily  hypothetical, 
it  is  difficult  to  see  how  any  theory  of  knowledge  can 
avoid  being  realistic.  Absolute  idealism,  with  its  hypo- 
thetical unity ;  and  mysticism,  with  its  ineffable  noetic  in- 
toxication, still  must  admit  that  the  finite  meaning,  in 
striving  for  its  completion,  implies  an  object  beyond  its 
internal  intent.  To  deny  this  is  to  fall  into  solipsism  or  to 
confuse  one's  self  with  the  absolute.  The  complete  absolute 
meaning  cannot  be  said  to  depend  for  its  existence  upon 


254  Truth  and  Reality 

our  finite  fragmentary  insight.     And  it  is  with  that  finite 
intent  that  our  problem  of  knowledge  is  concerned. 

II 

In  order  to  clear  the  way  for  realism,  we  must  get  rid  of 
some  fundamental  fallacies  which  permeate  most  of  our 
past  philosophic  thought.  One  of  these  fallacies  may  be 
stated  as  the  assumption  that  only  like  can  make  a  differ- 
ence to  like,  or  that  cause  and  effect  must  be  identical. 
This  has  been  assumed  as  an  axiom  by  idealism  and  mate- 
rialism alike.  For  idealism  and  materialism  are  alike  in- 
discriminative.  Their  method  is  dogmatic  rather  than 
critical.  The  only  difference  is  in  the  stuff  with  which 
they  start.  Idealism,  starting  with  meaning  stuff,  tries  to 
express  the  whole  universe  in  terms  of  this.  Materialism, 
starting  with  mechanical  stuff  —  stuff  indifferent  to  mean- 
ing and  value  —  must  be  consistent,  or  as  consistent  as  it 
can,  in  expressing  the  universe  in  terms  of  this.  Both  buy 
simplicity  at  the  expense  of  facts. 

The  problem  is  the  old  one  of  Empedocles :  Can  only 
like  make  a  difference  to  like  ?  "  For  it  is  with  earth  that 
we  see  Earth,  and  water  with  Water,  by  air  we  see  bright 
Air,  by  fire  destroying  Fire.  By  love  do  we  see  Love, 
and  Hate  by  grievous  hate."  Expressed  in  terms  of 
modern  idealism,  from  the  side  of  individual  consciousness, 
the  problem  would  read :  Can  only  experience  make  a  dif- 
ference to  experience ;  can  only  thought  make  a  difference 
to  thought  ?  The  absolute  idealist  attempts  this  disjunc- 
tion :  The  reality  which  we  strive  to  know  must  either  be 
part  of  one  context  with  our  own  finite  meaning,  must  be 
included  within  the  completed  purpose,  the  absolute  ex- 
perience, of  which  we  are  even  now  conscious  as  well  as 


Pragmatic  Realism  255 

of  our  finitude  and  fragmentariness ;  or,  on  the  other  hand, 
the  real  object  must  be  independent  of  our  thought  refer- 
ence, must  exist  wholly  outside  our  cognitive  context,  with- 
out being  capable  of  making  any  difference  to  it.  But 
complete  independence  is  meaningless ;  therefore  there 
must  be  one  inclusive  experience.  To  think  an  object  is 
to  think  it  as  experienced,  therefore  it  must  be  experience. 

The  issue  at  this  point  between  the  realist  and  the  ideal- 
ist is  a  two-fold  one.  The  realist  insists  that  there  can  be 
different  universes  of  experience  which  can  make  a  differ- 
ence lo  each  other ;  and  also  that  what  is  non-reflective  or 
non-meaning  can  make  a  difference  to  our  reflective  pur- 
poses, or  vice  versa.  We  can  reflect  upon  a  stone;  that 
makes  the  stone  experience  for  us.  But  does  it  also  make 
the  stone  as  such  experience  ?  It  is  as  reasonable,  at  any 
rate,  to  say  that  only  water  can  know  water,  and  that 
therefore  in  order  to  know  water  we  must  have  water  in 
the  eye  or  in  the  brain,  as  it  is  to  say  that  in  order  to 
know  the  stone  or  to  reflect  upon  the  stone,  the  stone  must 
be  reflective.  In  either  case  our  attitude  is  merely  dog- 
matic. That  objects  in  order  to  be  known  must  be  capable 
of  being  taken  again,  in  the  context  of  cognitive  experience, 
is,  of  course,  a  truism.  But  that  does  not  prove  that  they 
cannot  exist  without  being  known  or  that  they  must 
themselves  be  experience  in  order  to  be  known. 

Science  has  been  forced  to  abandon  the  axiom  that  only 
like  can  act  upon  like.  It  is  busy  remaking  its  mechanical 
models  in  order  to  meet  the  complexity  of  its  world. 
Chemical  energy  need  not  be  the  same  as  electrical  or 
nervous  energy,  to  make  a  difference  to  either.  Chemical 
energy  implies  weight  and  mass,  while  electrical  or  nerv- 
ous energy  does  not.  The  old  metaphysical  difficulty  in 


256  Truth  and  Reality 

regard  to  conscious  and  physical  energy  has  given  way  to 
a  question  of  fact.  The  question  is  not,  Can  they  make  a 
difference  to  each  other?  but,  Is  there  evidence  of  their 
making  any  difference  to  each  other  ?  A  cup  of  coffee  or 
a  good  beefsteak  makes  a  difference  to  thinking.  But  that 
does  not  necessarily  make  them  thought  stuff.  Whether 
cause  and  effect  are  identical,  either  in  time  or  in  kind,  is 
something  for  empirical  investigation  to  determine,  and  not 
to  be  settled  a  priori.  Science  presents  strong  evidence 
that  they  need  be  neither.  The  light  rays  may  have 
traveled  through  space  many  years  before  they  make  the 
difference  of  light  sensations  in  connection  with  our 
psycho-physical  organism ;  and  that  they  make  such  differ- 
ences does  not  prove  that  they  are  themselves  sensations. 

It  is  time  that  philosophy,  too,  were  abandoning  dogma- 
tism in  favor  of  facts.  It  is  no  longer  a  question  of  materi- 
alism or  idealism ;  but  we  must  use  idealistic  tools  where  we 
are  dealing  with  idealistic  stuff,  and  mechanical  categories 
where  the  evidence  for  consciousness  and  value  is  lacking. 
We  must  learn  to  respect  ends  where  there  are  ends ;  and 
to  use  as  means  those  facts  which  have  no  meaning  of 
their  own.  To  fail  thus  to  discriminate  is  to  be  a  senti- 
mentalist, on  the  one  hand,  or  a  bore,  on  the  other.  What 
we  want  is  a  grain  of  sanity,  even  the  size  of  a  mustard 
seed. 

The  merit  of  idealism,  and  for  this  we  ought  to  give  it 
due  credit,  is  that  it  has  shown  that  the  universe  must  be 
differentiated  with  reference  to  our  purposive  attitudes. 
This  is  true  whether  the  reality  to  be  known  is  purposive 
or  not.  Where  idealism  has  been  strong  is  in  interpreting 
institutional  life.  In  order  adequately  to  know  another 
meaning,  we  must  copy  or  share  that  meaning.  This  is  true 


Pragmatic  Realism  257 

whenever  our  reality  is  thought  stuff.  Idealism,  on  the 
other  hand,  has  always  been  weak  in  dealing  with  nature, 
and,  therefore,  in  furnishing  the  proper  setting  for  natural 
science.  Idealism  has  striven  to  institutionalize  nature  or 
to  reduce  nature  to  reflective  experience.  In  order  to  do 
this,  it  has  been  forced  either  to  insist  upon  the  phenome- 
nality  of  nature,  with  Berkeley  and  Green,  or  to  take  the 
ground  of  Hegel,  John  Caird  and  Royce,  that  nature  is  es- 
sentially thought,  social  experience,  the  objectification  of 
logical  categories,  though  an  sick  and  notfurstc/t,  i.e.,  only 
as  lived  over  by  reflective  experience.  Hence  nature  be- 
comes capable  of  system ;  it  is  essentially  systematic.  In 
thus  hypostatizing  the  unity  of  apperception  into  an  objec- 
tive unity  of  nature,  idealism  has  failed  to  discriminate. 
The  stone  and  Hamlet  are  lumped  together.  But  we  can- 
not acknowledge  or  react  on  nature  as  experience  on  its  own 
account,  and  therefore  idealism  breaks  down.  We  make  the 
conceptual  system  of  nature,  as  social  minds,  to  anticipate 
the  future  and  to  satisfy  our  needs.  The  meaning  of  the 
energy  that  satisfies,  and  of  the  transformations  by  which 
it  satisfies,  is  furnished  by  our  ideal  context.  That  water 
satisfies  thirst ;  that  fire  burns  wood  —  these  are  extra-sub- 
jective  energetic  relations.  But  the  why  must  be  fur- 
nished by  our  scientific  experience,  partial  and  fragmentary 
though  it  is. 

Materialism  has  been  quite  right  in  applying  the  mechani- 
cal categories  to  part  of  reality.  The  mechanical  ideals 
will  always  find  favor  in  natural  science,  where  the  aim  is 
not  the  understanding  of  an  objective  meaning,  but  control 
of  nature  for  our  purposes.  Where  the  materialist  shows 
his  dogmatism  is  in  applying  categories  which  are  conven- 
ient in  dealing  with  the  non-purposive  structure  of  the 


258  Truth  and  Reality 

world  to  institutional  reality  as  well.  In  failing  to  make 
them  work  here,  instead  of  calling  into  play  new  catego- 
ries, he  insists  upon  eliminating  the  refractory  world  of 
meaning  and  value,  while  the  idealist,  with  his  eye  primarily 
on  the  world  of  social  tissue  or  ideals,  has  insisted  that  the 
real  is  essentially  the  social  or  communicable.  Each  has 
failed  to  recognize  how  the  other  half  lives. 

Another  dogmatic  fallacy  which  has  been  committed  by 
idealists,  to  smooth  out  the  realistic  discontinuities  and 
ease  the  shock  of  actualities,  is  the  play  upon  the  implicit 
and  explicit.  I  would  not  say  that  the  category  of  the 
implicit  has  no  legitimate  use.  Wherever  we  are  dealing 
with  a  purposive  whole  of  any  kind,  intellectual,  ethical 
or  esthetic,  we  not  only  can  but  must  use  the  category  of 
the  implicit.  The  earlier  part  of  the  argument  must  im- 
ply or  foreshadow  the  later  within  the  logical  unity.  The 
earlier  part  of  the  dramatic  plot  must  find  its  fulfillment  in 
the  later ;  the  moral  struggle  points  to  an  ideal.  The  abuse 
of  the  category  of  the  implicit  comes  when  we  apply  our 
purposes  to  infra-purposive  realities.  Because  thinking  as 
a  process  arises  under  certain  structural  conditions  of  com- 
plexity, this  does  not  prove  that  earlier  and  simpler  stages 
of  development  must  be  treated  as  degrees  of  thinking. 
There  seem,  on  the  contrary,  to  be  qualitative  leaps  in  the 
genetic  series  of  experience,  not  reducible  to  the  quantita- 
tive category  of  degrees.  Thinking  is  a  new  fact  in  the 
series — furnishes  a  new  context  of  significance.  Again, 
because  we  systematize  nature  according  to  the  presuppo- 
sitions of  the  reflective  moment,  this  does  not  imply  a  re- 
flective unity  in  nature.  Here  again  there  seems  to  be  a 
discontinuity,  so  far  as  meaning  is  concerned,  which  thought 
must  acknowledge  and  cannot  bridge,  objectively,  at  any 


Pragmatic  Realism  259 

rate,  by  any  implicit  assumption  as  regards  thought's  own 
procedure. 

Another  current  dogmatic  fallacy  is  the  assumption 
that  because  we  take  contents  over  in  thinking  them, 
therefore  we  transmute  or  make  them  over,  if  indeed  we 
do  not  create  them  outright,  in  taking  account  of  them. 
But  the  transmutation  of  the  immediate  or  non-reflective 
has  to  do  with  its  significance,  not  its  content.  The  colors 
in  the  painting  are  the  same  that  we  have  seen  thousands 
of  times,  though  here  they  are  used  to  express  a  new  mean- 
ing. The  gold  we  think  about  has  precisely  the  same 
qualities  as  the  gold  which  was  present  as  an  object  of 
immediate  perception  or  esthetic  admiration.  It  does  not 
change  its  color  or  size  because  we  reflect  on  it.  It  is  the 
same  object  with  the  same  qualities  and  relations,  except 
that  much  of  the  existential  has  been  omitted  and  the  rela- 
tion of  cognitive  significance  has  been  superadded. 

Another  fallacy  is  the  assumption  that  what  is  not  stuff 
cannot  be  real.  This  assumption  is  very  old.  It  is  assumed 
by  Parmenides  when  he  dismisses  non-being  as  unthinkable 
and  unspeakable.  It  is  assumed  by  Kant  in  his  antimony 
of  space  and  time,  when  he  maintains  that  the  relation  to 
nothing  is  no  relation.  Most  philosophers  have  followed 
the  leadership  of  these  distinguished  thinkers.  But  the 
assumption  that  zero  is  unthinkable  and  that  the  relation 
to  nothing  is  no  relation  has  been  abandoned  by  mathe- 
matics for  logical  reasons.  There  is  no  more  important  rela- 
tion in  number  than  the  relation  to  zero.  The  limiting 
concept  of  zero  has  also  proved  of  great  value  in  metaphys- 
ics as  well  as  in  mathematics.  Take  space  for  example  : 
While  space  is  no  thing,  yet  as  distance  it  is  an  important 
condition  in  the  interaction  of  things. 


260  Truth  and  Reality 

III 

Instead  of  the  dogmatic  method  pursued  by  the  old  ideal- 
ism and  materialism  alike,  we  must  substitute  the  critical 
method.  This  method  has  been  rechristened  within  re- 
cent years  by  C.  S.  Peirce  and  William  James  and  called 
pragmatism.  As  I  understand  this  method,  it  means,  sim- 
ply, to  carry  the  scientific  spirit  into  metaphysics.  It  means 
the  willingness  to  acknowledge  reality  for  what  it  is ;  what 
it  is  always  meaning  for  us,  what  difference  it  makes  to 
our  reflective  purposes.  Instead  of  insisting  upon  identity 
of  stuff,  as  dogmatism  has  always  done,  this  method  is  dis- 
criminative. It  enables  us  to  break  up  the  universe  and 
to  deal  with  it  piecemeal,  to  recognize  unity  where  there 
is  unity  and  chaos  where  there  is  chaos,  purpose  where 
there  is  purpose  and  the  absence  of  purpose  where  there 
is  no  evidence  of  purpose.  The  universe  in  each  part  or 
stage  of  development  is  what  we  must  acknowledge  it  to 
be  —  not  necessarily  what  we  do  acknowledge,  but  what  we 
must  acknowledge  to  live  life  successfully.  This  acknowl- 
edgment, moreover,  is  not  a  mere  will  to  believe  or  voli- 
tional fiat,  but,  at  least  as  knowledge  becomes  organized,  a 
definite  and  forced  acknowledgment.  An  unlimited  will 
to  believe  as  regards  objective  reality  would  be  possible,  if 
at  all,  only  before  we  have  organized  knowledge,  that  is, 
if  you  could  imagine  knowledge  starting  in  a  conscious 
will-act.  When  we  already  have  organized  knowledge,  if 
we  choose  to  know,  the  possibilities  become  limited.  In 
case  of  fully  organized  knowledge,  the  place  of  the  indeter- 
minate will-to-believe  would  be  the  will-not-to-think,  that 
is,  to  commit  intellectual  suicide. 

We  can  not  state   the   truth   attitude  in   merely  sub- 


Pragmatic  Realism  261 

jective  terms.  The  truth  attitude  must  face  outward.  It 
must  orient  us  to  a  context  existing  on  its  own  account, 
whether  past  or  present.  In  such  orientation  or  such  ex- 
ternal meaning  lies  the  significance  of  truth.  The  truth 
attitude  cannot  be  characterized  as  merely  doubt  with  a 
transition  to  a  new  equilibrium,  and  as  ceasing  with  cer- 
tainty. The  truth  attitude  may  at  least  involve  the  con- 
sciousness that  we  know  that  we  know.  To  be  sure,  the 
nervousness  of  science  leads  us  to  repeat  the  experiment 
in  order  to  make  sure  that  we  have  made  no  mistake ;  but 

• 

that  does  not  alter  the  truth  of  our  first  finding,  if  the  ex- 
periment proves  correct.  Truth,  as  we  have  it,  involves 
two  things,  —  first,  luminousness,  or  a  peculiar  satisfaction 
to  the  individual  experience  at  the  time,  due  to  its  felt 
consistency  or  fluent  termination  in  its  intended  object. 
This  is  the  positive  truth  value,  whether  formal  or  factual. 
The  other  factor  involved  in  scientific  truth  is  the  feeling 
of  tentativeness  or  openness  to  correction.  This  is  a  quali- 
fication or  nervousness  on  the  part  of  the  truth  attitude, 
either  as  a  result  of  an  actual  feeling  of  discrepancy  and 
fragmentariness  as  regards  our  present  meaning;  or  it 
may  be  due  to  a  more  general  feeling  of  instability  based 
upon  our  finitude  and  the  time  character  of  our  meanings. 
Such  correction  can  only  come  through  further  experience, 
whether  of  the  immediate  or  formal  type.  We  cannot  say 
that  the  value  consists  in  the  future  consequences  or  lead- 
ings. These  obviously  have  no  value  until  they  come. 
Further  experience  furnishes  the  possibility  of  correction 
of  our  truth  values  and  so  of  producing  new  values.  I 
say  possibility  of  correction  because  repeating  the  experi- 
ment, while  it  relieves  our  nervousness,  does  not  necessarily 
produce  a  new  truth.  The  truth  meaning  must  first  be 


262  Truth  and  Reality 

stated  in  schematic  terms  on  the  basis  of  the  data  as  we 
have  them  and  then  tried  out  in  terms  of  consequences. 
Such  consequences  must  be  in  part  present  to  us  as  a  re- 
sult of  past  experience.  We  do  not  formulate  theories  in 
vacuo.  If  the  truth  value  lay  merely  in  the  future  conse- 
quences or  leadings,  there  could  be  no  such  thing  as  truth 
value.  Truth  must  face  backward  in  order  to  face  for- 
ward. It  is  Janus  faced. 

We  may  lay  it  down,  then,  that  the  real  must  be  known 
through  our  purposive  attitudes  or  conceptual  construction. 
Real  objects  are  never  constituted  by  mere  sense  percep- 
tion. They  are  not  compounds  of  sensations.  Sensations 
are  our  awareness  of  the  going  on  of  certain  physiological 
changes,  whether  connected  with  an  extra-organic  world 
or  not.  They  cannot  be  said,  therefore,  to  constitute 
things.  These  presuppose  selective  purpose.  They  can 
only  become  objects  for  a  self -realizing  will.  The  real  is 
the  intelligible  or  noumenal,  not  the  mere  immediate ;  and 
by  the  noumenal  I  mean  what  we  must  meet,  what  reality 
must  be  taken  as  in  our  procedure,  as  opposed  to  our  sen- 
sations. It  is  through  conative  purpose  that  knowledge  of 
the  character  of  our  world  becomes  possible.  The  imme- 
diate, however,  must  furnish  the  evidence  ;  in  the  language 
of  James  it  puts  us  next  to  the  real  object.  It  establishes 
energetic  continuity  with  the  intended  context  of  reality. 

Empiricism  is  at  best  a  halfway  house.  We  cannot  say 
that  the  real  is  merely  what  is  perceived  or  what  makes  an 
immediate  difference  to  our  conscious  purposes,  whether 
in  the  way  of  value  or  of  fact.  We  must  at  least  say  that 
the  real  is  what  can  be  perceived,  unless  we  bring  in  some 
deus  ex  machina  or  supernatural  storehouse  of  percepts,  as 
Berkeley  does.  Surely  the  empirical  idealist  of  to-day 


Pragmatic  Realism  263 

would  not  say  that  the  increased  powers  of  the  telescope 
or  microscope  create  the  facts.  Nor  can  the  uniformity  of 
our  expectancies  be  credited  to  our  individual  perception ; 
and  hence  from  the  perceptualist  point  of  view,  it  requires 
another  deus  ex  machina.  To  say  that  uniformity  or 
stability  is  a  social  fact  does  not  explain  the  fact,  but 
presupposes  an  extra-social  constitution,  a  constitution 
binding  upon  all  of  us.  Not  only  perception,  but  possible 
perception  must  be  invoked  to  complete  the  empirical 
idealist's  reality ;  and  "  possible  "  itself  is  not  a  category 
of  perception. 

As  the  old  idealist  and  the  old  realist  alike  assumed  the 
qualitative  identity  of  cause  and  effect,  it  became  necessary 
to  think  of  subjective  states  as  copies  of  external  qualities. 
Na'fve  realism  and  idealism  alike  assume  this  copy-relation 
of  the  subjective  on  one  hand  and  the  real  qualities  on  the 
other.  In  modified  realism,  the  primary  qualities  at  least 
must  be  copied.  For  the  empirical  idealism  of  to-day  the 
problem  still  remains  as  to  whether  the  perceptions  and 
the  objective  qualities  are  the  same.  Unless  the  idealist 
becomes  a  solipsist  he  must  show  that  his  subjective  copies 
are  adequate  to  a  world  as  existent.  This  difficulty  would 
vanish,  once  we  abandoned  the  dogmatic  and  unintelligible 
duplication  of  qualities,  as  though  qualities  could  exist 
passively  by  themselves.  Qualities  are  energies.  They 
are  what  objects  must  be  taken  as  in  determinate  contexts. 
To  ask  what  perceptual  qualities  are,  when  they  are  not 
perceived,  becomes  in  that  case  as  superfluous  as  it  is 
meaningless.  Processes,  of  which  we  are  not  conscious, 
have  no  perceptual  qualities,  unless,  under  certain  other 
conditions,  they  can  make  perceptual  differences  to  beings 
organized  as  we  are.  To  speak  of  archetypal  qualities  is 


264  Truth  and  Reality 

merely  duplicating  this  moment  of  perception — to  take 
what  exists  in  a  context  as  an  abstract  idea.  If  these  non- 
conscious  reals  act  upon  other  non-conscious  reals,  we 
have  not  perceptual  differences,  but  chemical  or  physical 
changes.  These  must  be  interpolated  by  us  in  order  to 
make  continuous  our  perceptual  scheme.  We  saw  the 
wood  burning  in  the  grate :  in  our  absence  the  fire  has 
gone  out  and  the  wood  has  turned  to  ashes.  To  piece  to- 
gether this  discontinuity  in  our  perceptions,  we  must  assume 
certain  differences  or  changes  which  cannot  themselves  be 
expressed  as  perceptions.  And  thus  we  come  to  realize 
that  while  we  must  take  some  qualities  of  things  as  exist- 
ing as  part  of  our  perceptual  context,  we  must  also  take 
other  qualities  as  existing  independent  of  perception  in 
their  own  dynamic  thing-contexts,  which  we  can  read  off 
a  posteriori  and  predict  under  determinate  conditions. 

Perceptual  qualities,  therefore,  are  not  the  only  qualities. 
Even  granting  a  being  who  should  have  perceptual  differ- 
ences for  all  the  changes  going  on,  minute  or  great,  and 
without  breach  of  continuity,  he  would  not  have  a 
complete  account  of  reality.  The  real  individual  cannot 
be  exhausted  as  a  compound  of  perceptual  qualities.  He 
must  be  acknowledged  as  something  more  than  the  sum 
total  of  his  sense  appearances,  past,  present  and  future. 
If  sensations  alone  constituted  reality,  then  the  more  sen- 
sations the  more  reality.  Take  Helen  Keller's  reality,  for 
example,  on  this  supposition.  For  convenience,  I  will  use 
Professor  Titchener's  estimate  of  the  number  and  kinds  of 
sensations,  leaving  aside  the  question  here  as  to  whether 
all  sensations  can  be  taken  as  sense  qualities.  According 
to  him,  sight  furnishes  us  32,820  different  sensations, 
hearing  11,600,  making  a  total  of  44,420.  As  Helen 


Pragmatic  Realism  265 

Keller  possesses  neither  the  sense  of  sight  nor  that  of 
hearing,  her  reality  would  be  to  our  reality  as  15  is  to 
44,435.  But  Helen  Keller  seems  to  be  able  to  enter  into 
communion  with  human  beings  all  over  the  world,  to  share 
their  purposes,  to  sympathize  with  them  and  help  them  better 
than  most  human  beings  with  the  use  of  all  their  senses. 

The  reason  the  position  that  reality  is  the  sum  of  its 
perceptions  has  seemed  so  plausible  lies  partly  in  the 
fallacious  use  of  the  method  of  agreement,  partly  in  the 
confusion  between  the  causa  cognoscendi  and  the  causa 
essendi.  The  perceptual  qualities  do  exist;  and  it  is 
through  them  we  become  immediately  conscious  of  an 
external  world.  Objects  are  what  they  are  perceived  as, 
but  indefinitely  more.  We  must  not  forget  that  there  are 
other  contexts,  such  as  the  multitudinous  thing-contexts 
and  the  contexts  of  our  will  attitudes.  These  may  be 
practically  more  significant  for  determining  the  reality  of  a 
thing  than  our  sensations  —  not  all  of  which  can  be  treated 
as  sense  qualities.  It  may  be  of  more  practical  significance 
for  the  nature  of  water  that  it  satisfies  thirst  than  that  it 
gives  us  a  number  of  contact  reactions.  When  we  come  to 
deal  with  a  human  being,  a  friend  of  ours,  the  inadequacy 
of  mere  perceptual  qualities  becomes  even  more  evident. 
He  is  not  to  be  taken  merely  as  his  height,  nor  his  color, 
nor  his  softness,  nor  his  hardness,  nor  even  the  sum  total 
of  all  the  perceptions  we  can  get.  He  is  primarily  what 
we  must  acknowledge,  what  fulfills  a  unique  purpose  on 
the  part  of  our  wills,  and,  as  opposed  to  the  gold  or  the 
stone,  a  reality  with  an  inner  meaning  which  we  can  to 
some  extent  copy. 

We  have  seen  that  experience  becomes  truth  only 
through  conceptual  construction  or  purposive  will  attitudes. 


266  Truth  and  Reality 

Percepts  only  become  cognitively  significant  as  termini  of 
ideal  construction,  as  verification  stuff.  No  wonder  that 
the  perceptualists  have  not  been  able  to  discover  non-being 
dimensions,  since  these  could  not  be  perceived,  but  dis- 
covered only  through  the  most  subtle  conceptual  tools,  ac- 
cording to  the  real  difference  which  they  make  to  our  pur- 
posive striving.  We  have  already  indicated  that  because 
reality  can  only  be  known  through  conceptual  construction, 
that  does  not  mean  that  reality  must  be  conceptual. 
Reality  is,  however,  knowable  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  con- 
ceptualized. In  recognizing  that  reality  could  not  be 
treated  altogether  as  purpose,  moral  or  intellectual,  Kant 
showed  a  keenness  far  exceeding  that  of  his  critics. 

Since  perceptual  qualities  are  the  felt  continuities  or 
functional  connections  of  energetic  centers,  when  a  con- 
scious agent  is  part  of  the  complex,  there  can  be  no  sense 
in  speaking  of  these  qualities  as  either  acting  upon  the  will 
or  parallel  to  the  world  of  will  acts.  The  perceptual 
qualities  do  not  exist  independent  of  the  concrete  situation, 
so  that  they  could  act  upon  it.  They  are  what  the  object 
must  be  taken  as,  or  known  as,  in  the  special  psycho- 
physical  context.  They  preexist  only  potentially,  i.e.,  as 
what  the  object  can  be  taken  as  in  the  determinate  con- 
text. They  are,  however,  only  one  type  of  transeunt  con- 
nections or  energetic  continuities.  These  energetic 
continuities  may  be  intersubjective  relations,  and  in  that 
case  communication  and  conceptual  understanding  are 
possible.  They  may  be  relations  to  centers  below  the 
reflective  level.  In  that  case  knowledge  becomes  instru- 
mental—  a  reweaving  of  a  non-meaning  context  into  the 
unity  of  our  purposes. 

Equipped  with  our  subjective  purposes,  or  conceptual 


Pragmatic  Realism  267 

tools,  we  can  confront  the  larger  world.  In  the  course  of 
conscious  experience,  as  we  strive  to  realize  our  tendencies, 
formal  or  practical,  the  world  beyond  us  becomes  differen- 
tiated and  labeled  according  to  our  success  or  failure.  But 
the  real  objects  are  not  constituted  by  our  differentiation, 
except  when  we  make  our  realities  outright,  as  in  the  case 
of  artistic  creation.  The  meaning  for  us  is,  indeed,  created 
in  the  course  of  experience,  but  not  the  objects  which  we 
mean.  Else  science  were  impossible.  The  real  objects 
must  be  acknowledged  or  met,  whether  they  are  to  be  un- 
derstood or  to  be  controlled. 

The  world  of  real  objects  may  be  differentiated  into  two 
general  divisions,  the  world  of  being  or  stuff,  on  the  one 
hand,  and  the  world  of  non-being  or  non-stuff,  on  the  other. 
By  the  former  I  understand  various  types  of  expectancy 
or  uniformity,  which  we  can  have  in  regard  to  our  percept- 
ual world.  These  types  of  uniformity,  again,  can  be  graded 
into  two  main  divisions,  namely,  those  which  we  can  ac- 
knowledge metaphysically  as  purposive  in  their  own  right 
and  those  we  must  acknowledge  as  existing  and  must  meet, 
but  which  have  no  inwardness  or  value  on  their  own  ac- 
count. The  former  we  must  learn  to  understand  and  ap- 
preciate, the  latter  to  anticipate  and  control.  The  former 
constitute  the  realm  of  idealism,  the  latter  of  materialism. 
As  regards  the  stuff  character  of  reality,  this  theory  is 
frankly  pluralistic,  acknowledging  different  kinds  and 
grades  of  energetic  centers  according  to  the  differences 
they  make  to  our  reflective  purposes. 

But  we  must  also  take  account  of  the  non-stuff  dimen- 
sions of  reality.  These  differ  from  the  stuff  types  in  that 
they  are  not  perceptually  continuous  with  our  psycho-physi- 
cal organism.  They  cannot  appear  as  immediate  phenom- 


268  Truth  and  Reality 

ena,  but  still  must  be  acknowledged  for  the  realization  of  our 
purposes.  Thus  we  must  actfpwledge  the  transformation 
of  our  values,  the  instability  of  our  meanings.  Time 
creeps  into  our  equations  and  makes  revision  necessary. 
New  values  can  only  be  had  by  waiting.  Again,  space,  as 
distance,  abstracting  from  the  content  of  space,  conditions 
our  intersubjective  relations,  as  well  as  our  relations  to 
non-purposive  beings.  It  makes  possible  externality  of 
energetic  centers  and  free  mobility.  Further,  the  relativity 
of  our  meanings  and  ideals  makes  necessary  the  assumption 
of  an  absolute  direction,  a  normative  limit,  to  measure  the 
validity  of  our  finite  standards.  Lastly,  we  find  it  conven- 
ient to  abstract  the  fact  of  consciousness  from  the  psychic 
contents  and  the  conative  attitudes.  While  our  awareness 
is  intermittent,  the  conative  attitudes  and  purposes  may  be 
comparatively  constant.  These  non-stuff  dimensions  must 
be  regarded  as  real  as  the  will  centers  which  they  condition. 
They  are  more  knowable  than  the  world  of  stuff,  because 
their  characters  are  few  and  simple,  whereas  the  varieties 
and  contexts  of  stuff  are  almost  infinite.  Thus,  by  means 
of  our  conceptual  tools,  we  are  able  to  discover  not  only 
various  kinds  of  stuff,  but  we  are  able  to  discover  dimen- 
sions of  reality  of  ultimate  importance,  where  microscopes 
and  telescopes  cannot  penetrate  —  realities  which  eye  hath 
not  seen  nor  ear  heard,  nor  ever  will  see  or  hear,  more 
subtle  than  ether  or  radium. 


CHAPTER   XV 
THE  OBJECT  AND  ITS  CONTEXTS 

To  avoid  confusion,  it  is  well  to  distinguish  at  the  out- 
set between  reality  as  the  object  of  our  knowledge  and  as 
our  object-construct.  The  real  object  is  that  which  we 
must  meet,  to  which  we  must  adjust  ourselves,  in  order  to 
live  to  the  fullest  extent.  The  object-construct,  or  the 
scientific  context,  is  the  sum  of  our  knowledge  or  definitions 
about  reality,  our  series  and  other  conceptual  tools  by 
means  of  which  we  strive  to  describe  and  reconstruct  our 
world.  Ask  the  scientist  about  energy,  ether,  gravitation, 
or  water,  and  he  immediately  empties  himself  of  his  physi- 
cal and  astronomical  equations,  his  chemical  formulae,  etc. 
These  are  the  scientific  elaborations  of  experience  for  our 
convenience  and  need  not  be  like  the  facts  they  aim  to 
manipulate.  The  equations  of  Newton  are  not  like  the  facts 
or  changes  that  gravitation  symbolizes.  We  thus  elaborate 
our  world  into  various  series  or  contexts,  by  means  of 
which  we  strive  to  anticipate  the  real  object.  We  must 
distinguish,  in  other  words,  between  the  cognitive  context, 
on  the  one  hand,  and  the  context  of  the  object,  which  we 
strive  to  know,  on  the  other. 

OBJECTIVE    CONTEXTS 

Every  fact  can  be  taken  in  several  contexts.  It  can  be 
taken  in  a  physical  context  as  part  of  the  interacting  world 
in  space ;  and  it  can  be  taken  in  a  psychological  context, 

269 


2/O  Truth  and  Reality 

individual  or  social.  Thus  the  content,  sun,  is  part  of  a 
world  of  physical  processes  and  known  to  us  by  the  differ- 
ences it  makes  to  other  physical  things  and  to  our  psycho- 
physical  organism.  The  sun  is  also  a  concept  with  a 
history  and  place  in  our  thought  development,  individual 
and  social.  Whether  we  can  know  has,  therefore,  a  three- 
fold meaning.  It  may  fefer  to  the  possibility  of  taking  the 
same  meaning  twice  within  the  one  stream  of  experience, 
or  to  the  possibility  of  two  knowers  having  the  same  mean- 
ing, or  to  the  sameness  of  the  physical  object.  In  any  case 
the  problem  is  difficult  enough,  but  it  can  be  simplified  by 
proceeding  upon  an  empirical  instead  of  an  a  priori  basis. 
By  this  method  we  shall  at  least  not  multiply  difficulties. 

Can  we  take  an  object  or  fact  twice  in  our  individual 
history  ?  Can  we  logically  take  a  meaning  over  without 
doing  violence  to  it  ?  Can  we  know  the  past  ?  Obviously, 
unless  this  is  possible,  identity  anywhere  else  is  meaning- 
less, for  all  knowing  in  the  end  must  be  individual  meaning. 
Social  reference  itself  must  have  its  basis  in  individual 
constitution.  The  ultimate  evidence  for  the  existence  of 
sameness  must  be  the  individual  feeling  of  sameness, 
though  this  sameness  of  conscious  functioning  presupposes 
a  degree  of  structural  uniformity  on  the  part  of  reality 
which  makes  the  intuition  of  memory  and  familiarity  possi- 
ble. The  principle  of  indiscernibles  is  at  any  rate  valuable 
as  a  pragmatic  principle.  We  may  indeed  have  a  priori 
reasons,  and  empirical  too,  for  suspecting  the  naive  feeling 
of  sameness,  even  unaided  by  microscopes,  but  we  cannot 
wholly  discredit  it  without  discrediting  the  judging  process 
itself.  We  must  hold  that  what  can  be  taken  as  the  same 
is  the  same  or  practically  so.  There  is  of  course  the  sup- 
plementary social  test,  in  any  particular  case,  viz.,  that 


The  Object  and  its  Contexts  271 

others  can  recognize  our  attitudes,  our  meaningful  func- 
tioning, as  the  same  or  different,  and  so  correct  our  patho- 
logical feelings.  But  the  others,  too,  are,  after  all,  strands 
of  individual  history.  If  the  consciousness  of  every  indi- 
vidual were  evanescent,  there  could  be  no  more  recognition 
of  the  sameness  of  other  meanings  than  of  our  own.  That 
they  can  mean  that  I  am  the  same  must,  in  the  end,  come 
back  to  the  continuity  of  each  individual  meaning.  Apart 
from  such  a  continuity,  social  and  physical  sameness  would 
be  alike  meaningless.  Our  meanings,  then,  like  our  objec- 
tive individuals,  are  the  same  just  in  so  far  as  we  can 
acknowledge  them  to  be  the  same.  My  concept,  sun,  still 
means  the  same  sun,  has  the  same  perceptual  nucleus  of 
shiny  disk  and  its  apparent  motion,  however  much  it  may 
have  been  enriched  by  astronomical  study. 

That  the  past,  in  so  far  as  it  has  meaning  for  us,  exists 
as  a  part  of  the  present  cognitive  context  is  a  truism. 
When  it  is  not  thus  taken  up  into  the  present  context,  it 
persists  potentially  as  dispositions,  manuscripts,  or  geologi- 
cal strata.  It  is  not  well,  however,  to  press  this  a  priori 
argument,  derived  from  the  nature  of  the  apperceptive 
context,  too  far.  If  the  past  were  altogether  fluent,  we 
could  not  reconstruct  it  at  all.  It  never  could  mean  past 
to  us.  It  must  have  a  content  of  its  own,  even  though  the 
cognitive  context  has  changed.  Pure  nothing  could  not 
afford  a  basis  for  serial  construction.  In  geological  trans- 
formations, the  ribs  of  the  old  strata  do  stand  out  with  an 
individuality  of  their  own,  furnishing  the  basis  for  our  ideal 
perspective.  And  in  psychological  development,  too,  we 
must  recognize  the  ribs  —  certain  structures  which  still 
stand  out  as  individuals  with  their  own  meaning,  though 
in  the  atmosphere  of  the  present  setting.  We  must  feel 


2/2  Truth  and  Reality 

the  functional  identity  of  the  past  in  the  present.  Here, 
too,  we  have  record,  the  retentiveness  of  the  individual 
mind.  The  old  meanings  remain.  They  cling  to  their 
structural  conditions  as  the  vine  to  its  artificial  support. 
They  do  not  simply  flow  into  the  next  moment,  for  we  can 
acknowledge  and  compare  their  own  meanings  with  the 
new  meanings  which  have  replaced  them.  While  the  past 
meanings  are  past  so  far  as  being  our  personal  meanings 
is  concerned,  they  are  not  past  as  ideal  structures.  As 
such  they  can  still  become  memories,  to  be  re-lived  when 
the  light  of  consciousness  is  thrown  on  them  again,  even 
though  their  place  in  the  growth  series  makes  them  have 
the  feeling  of  pastness.  They  are  part-minds  —  resur- 
rected, dynamically  continuous  with,  but  not  created  by, 
the  present  subject.  They  must  be  acknowledged  as 
having  their  own  setting  and  meaning  independent  of  the 
meaning  and  value  which  they  have  in  our  present  cogni- 
tive context.  They  figure  thus  in  two  teleological  contexts ; 
and  these  again  owe  their  continuity  to  their  figuring  in  a 
world  of  physical  processes. 

The  dating  of  this  sequence  of  meanings  would  be  con- 
jectural beyond  a  few  seconds,  if  it  were  not  for  the  tag  of 
the  chronological  system  associated  with  the  structures. 
Except  for  this  artificial  time  coefficient,  the  understanding 
of  past  structures  does  not  differ  essentially  from  the  pres- 
ent. They  do  not  differ  necessarily  in  vividness  or  dis- 
tinctness from  experiences  much  more  recent.  These 
characters  depend  upon  other  conditions  besides  lapse  of 
time.  The  difference  again  in  the  feeling  of  intimacy  be- 
tween our  own  past  meanings  and  other  meanings  must  be 
sought  in  the  difference  in  functional  continuity  with  the 
present.  This  gives  the  former  a  different  intuitional 


The  Object  and  its  Contexts  273 

value.  But  this  intuition  of  familiarity  may  fail  even  as 
regards  my  own  successive  contexts.  The  part-minds  or 
associative  contexts  of  the  past  may  become  dynamically 
discontinuous  with  each  other  and  with  the  present  context, 
as  in  multiple  personality.  In  such  a  case  we  no  longer 
put  the  personal  stamp  upon  them.  We  know  them,  if  at 
all,  as  we  do  the  contexts  of  other  egos.  And  even  in  or- 
dinary life,  we  may  depend  entirely  upon  records  for  our 
own  past.  The  interpretation  of  our  past,  in  any  case,  is 
not  a  matter  of  knowing  the  brain  continuities,  if  we  did 
know  them,  but  an  immediate  recognition  of  the  meanings 
themselves,  whether  brought  to  us  by  the  processes  of  as- 
sociation or  objective  records,  though  this  does  not  dis- 
prove the  dependence  of  our  sense  of  continuity  upon 
physical  processes. 

So  socialized  is  our  experience,  so  strung  out  upon  the 
conventional  measures  of  time  and  space,  so  associated 
with  language,  that  the  interpretation  of  meanings — even 
of  our  own  past  — is  largely  an  interpretation  of  language. 
Words  and  their  contexts  are  the  social  correlates  of  our 
meanings,  in  our  trying  to  understand  ourselves  as  well  as 
each  other.  Brain  correlation,  however  real  it  may  be  in 
the  world  of  causal  explanation,  has  no  relevancy  to  our  in- 
terpreting of  meanings.  The  support  of  the  world  of  mean- 
ings is  language  and  social  institutions.  And  here  we  can 
develop  our  ideal  relations,  quite  independent  of  our  igno- 
rance of  brain  dynamics.  Logic  and  ethics  were  full- 
fledged  sciences  before  physiology  could  be  said  to  exist 

But  contents  must  be  taken  not  merely  as  figuring  in  the 
context  of  individual  experience,  they  must  also  be  taken  as 
figuring  in  historic  social  experience.  Here  a  serious  prob- 
lem arises  from  the  fact  that  we  have  to  recognize  a  num- 


274  Truth  and  Reality 

her  of  coexisting  and  overlapping  individual  contexts.  As 
these  contexts  cannot  be  treated  as  mere  duplicates,  the 
problem  of  knowing  the  same  object  takes  another  form, 
viz.,  whether  there  can  be  universal  objects  or  objects  for 
several  knowers.  Here  again  the  test  must  be  empirical. 
We,  as  several  knowers,  do  seem  to  be  able,  in  spite  of  the 
seeming  incommensurability  of  the  contexts,  to  refer  to  the 
same  content,  to  agree  and  to  act  together.  The  discrep- 
ancies of  different  fields  of  consciousness,  their  different 
fringes  of  significance,  must  be  settled  by  the  same  induc- 
tive tests  that  any  other  problem  involves,  not  simply  be  de- 
duced a  priori.  Such  experiments,  for  ascertaining,  for 
example,  the  difference  in  associative  constellations  in  dif- 
ferent individuals,  have  already  been  carried  on  by  Munster- 
berg  and  others.  Such  differences,  however,  have  to  do 
with  the  imagery  of  the  meaning,  not  its  final  intent  or  ref- 
erence to  an  objective  world. 

Through  the  common  understandings  of  the  several  sub- 
jects we  build  up  the  world  of  science,  institutions  and 
beauty.  These  unities  come  to  be  recognized  as  existing 
on  their  own  account.  True,  these  social  contexts,  as  the 
past  contexts,  must  figure  in  the  cognitive  context  of  the 
individual  subject.  They  must  become  known  through 
the  agreement  of  the  idea  with  its  intended  consequences 
within  individual  experience.  But  we  must  acknowledge,  as 
independent  of  the  cognitive  context,  an  objective  context 
in  which  the  facts  have  their  own  relation  and  significance, 
which  we  must  respect.  Like  individual  experience,  social 
experience  shows  its  dependence  upon  physical  continuity 
for  records,  by  means  of  which  the  meaning  can  be  handed 
on  to  the  future. 

We  have  been  forced  to  take  account  of  two  forms  of 


The  Object  and  its  Contexts  275 

identity,  teleological  identity  and  physical  identity.  The 
former  has  presented  two  kinds  of  problems,  viz.,  Can 
present  subjects  know  the  same  meaning  as  past  subjects 
within  the  same  history  ?  And  can  one  individual  subject 
know  the  same  meaning  that  other  subjects  know?  In 
either  case,  teleological  identity  is  closely  dependent  upon 
physical  identity.  For  my  sharing  my  own  past,  or  the 
possibility  of  memory,  is  dependent  upon  processes,  not 
themselves  experience.  Else  there  would  be  no  continuity 
of  waking  moments  with  each  other.  Social  agreement, 
too,  involves  a  physical  constitution  which  makes  continuity 
of  centers  in  space  possible  and  which  concerns  those 
records  from  which  we  can  reconstruct  our  meanings  in 
time.  Identity  of  meaning  is  impossible  unless  we  can 
take  our  physical  objects  twice. 

Nature,  as  our  system  of  knowledge,  is  our  social  con- 
struct, with  its  systematized  expectancies  as  reduced  to 
scientific  technique.  Yet,  while  physical  science  is  a  social 
institution,  we  cannot  recognize  its  object  as  a  social  insti- 
tution. We  must  distinguish  between  communicative  pro- 
cesses, which  we  can  acknowledge  as  having  a  meaning  or 
purpose  of  their  own,  and  non-communicative  processes 
which  we  must  deal  with  in  a  merely  external  way.  While 
both  have  their  own  context,  independent  of  the  context  of 
our  cognitive  purpose,  \b&  context  of  the  physical  processes 
is  not  one  of  meaning,  but  of  causality.  The  physical  pro- 
cesses furnish  a  limit  which  our  ideal  construction  must 
meet.  They  are  not  mere  phenomena.  We  must  recognize 
physical  things  as  figuring  in  their  own  context  of  physical 
interactions,  within  their  own  space  constellations,  and  their 
own  history  of  cumulative'changes,  though  they  also  figure, 
as  contents,  within  social  experience  and  within  the  individual 


276  Tntth  and  Reality 

conscious  moment  of  perception  and  interpretation.  Only 
the  latter  contexts  have  meaning  and  value  bound  up  with 
them.  The  former  means  a  context  for  our  ideal  construc- 
tion merely. 

Existentially,  if  not  Ideologically,  our  relation  to  nature 
is  bipolar.  We  do  not  make  the  gravitational  differences, 
the  interstellar  distances  and  the  geological  strata  when 
we  take  account  of  them.  They  acquire  significance,  not 
existence,  when  they  are  taken  over  out  of  their  own  con- 
text into  our  cognitive  context.  The  latter  must  tally  in 
its  coexistences  and  sequences  with  the  intended  context  of 
nature  as  perceived,  if  we  are  to  anticipate  successfully  its 
facts.  However  much  we  socialize  nature  in  our  scientific 
procedure,  science  itself  becomes  meaningless  unless  we 
also  respect  nature  as  having  its  own  context. 

We  have  seen  that  the  processes,  which  we  must  take 
account  of,  exist  in  three  types  of  context.  They  figure  in 
the  world  of  interacting  energies,  with  their  causal  and 
space  relations ;  they  figure  in  the  social  contexts  —  in 
science  and  institutions,  which  we  must  imitate  and  react 
upon ;  they  figure  in  the  special  context  of  each  individual, 
as  he  tries  to  appropriate  the  processes  as  part  of  his  world 
of  meanings.  In  studying  the  record  of  Thales  or  taking 
account  of  our  own  meaning  of  yesterday,  all  three  contexts 
are  involved. 

RELATION  OF  THE  CONTEXTS  TO  EACH  OTHER 

What  relation  do  these  contexts  bear  to  each  other  ?  The 
physical  sun  out  in  space  and  my  meaning  sun  are  both 
real  structures.  They  make  a  real  difference  to  each  other. 
My  meaning  is  not  merely  a  passive  picture,  but  a  conative 
tendency,  an  energy  which  leads  to  certain  motor  con- 


The  Object  and  its  Contexts  277 

sequences,  at  least  so  far  as  my  own  body  is  concerned. 
The  differences  ray  purpose  makes  to  the  sun  are  negligible 
for  scientific  purposes.  And  so  we  come  to  treat  the  pro- 
cess as  one-sided.  But  while  we  may,  for  certain  purposes, 
ignore  the  differences  our  thoughts  make  to  the  physical 
world,  we  must,  nevertheless,  in  order  to  have  knowledge, 
assume  that  the  universe  is  a  dynamic  whole.  The  thought 
structure  must  be  dynamically  part  of  the  same  world  with 
the  sun  structure.  It  hangs  together  with  the  sun,  medi- 
ately at  least,  by  hanging  together  with  our  own  nervous 
system  and  through  the  control  it  exercises  over  it  and  the 
bodily  movements.  Every  fact  must  be  capable  of  making 
a  difference,  directly  or  through  intermediaries,  to  other 
facts,  and  especially  to  human  nature,  to  make  knowledge 
possible.  Hence  parallelism  is  an  impossible  theory.  It  is 
well  to  remember  that  our  splitting  the  world  into  ideal 
series,  such  as  mind  and  body,  does  not  affect  the  continuity 
of  the  energetic  relations  of  the  real  world. 

When  we  come  to  the  relation  of  the  context  of  individ- 
ual meaning  to  the  social  context,  it  is  easier  to  see  how 
one  makes  a  difference  to  the  other.  All  thinking,  how- 
ever many  private  frills  and  corruscations  it  may  have,  is 
social  thinking.  It  can  develop  only,  and  become  valid  only, 
in  response  to  social  needs.  On  the  other  hand,  the  very 
existence  of  a  social  context  is  due  to  the  overlappings, 
the  common  attitudes  and  contents,  of  individual  minds. 
This  is  true  practically  as  well  as  theoretically.  Mutual 
trust  or  distrust  makes  all  the  difference  between  economic 
confidence  and  social  stability,  on  one  hand,  and  panic  and 
anarchy,  on  the  other.  In  the  plastic  world  of  inter- 
subjective  relations,  our  understanding  each  other's  mean- 
ings and  our  will  attitudes  toward  each  other  do  make 


278  Truth  and  Reality 

decided  and  recognizable  differences  to  the  structures  in- 
volved, individual  or  social. 

When  we  come  to  the  past  contexts  again,  here  we  must 
recognize  a  different  relation.  While  these  contexts  can 
and  do  make  a  difference  to  the  living  present,  send  their 
radiation  on  as  we  restore  continuity  with  them,  we  can- 
not in  turn  influence  them.  We  cannot  change  the  con- 
tent of  Homer's  Iliad  by  our  thinking  about  it,  though  we 
can  change  its  meaning  and  value  for  ourselves. 

Our  relation  to  the  physical  world  is  existentially  bipolar, 
as  we  must  acknowledge  the  existence  of  nature,  but  it  is 
Ideologically  unipolar,  as  nature  has  significance  and 
value  only  as  taken  up  into  the  context  of  human  nature. 
We  must  acknowledge  Mt.  Washington  as  existent ;  but 
we  cannot  acknowledge  it  as  having  an  inner  meaning  or 
halo  of  value  of  its  own.  While  all  our  meaning  contexts, 
individual  and  social,  must  hang  on  nature  for  records,  it 
must  hang  on  them  for  significance.  Our  relation  to  the 
social  context,  again,  is  both  existentially  bipolar  and  teleo- 
logically  bipolar,  as  we  must  acknowledge  the  other  sub- 
jects both  as  existing  on  their  own  account  and  possessing 
a  meaning  of  their  own.  In  talking  with  a  friend  we 
must  both  acknowlege  him  as  existing  and  as  having  a 
meaning,  independent  of  our  cognitive  attitude.  The 
past,  finally,  we  must  take  as  teleologically  bipolar,  for  we 
must  acknowledge  that  the  past  contexts  have  a  meaning 
of  their  own.  We  do  not  create  the  meaning  of  the  Iliad, 
or  our  meaning  of  yesterday,  by  taking  account  of  it.  But 
the  relation  is  existentially  unipolar,  for  the  past-subject 
itself  has  ceased  to  exist.  The  creator  of  the  Homeric 
meaning  is  no  more. 

Each  context,  finally,  must  be  recognized,  by  the  cogni- 


The  Object  and  its  Contexts  279 

tive  subject,  as  having  its  own  perspective  and  its  own 
rate  of  motion.  While  the  same  content,  sun,  figures  as 
part  of  the  physical  world  ;  in  the  context  of  social  history ; 
and  in  individual  history,  the  physical  history  of  the  sun, 
with  its  dizzy  figures,  bears  no  proportion  to  the  history  of 
the  social  concept,  sun ;  or  its  cognizing  in  individual  ex- 
perience. And  in  each  case  the  object  must  be  recognized 
as  qualified  by  the  relations  or  laws  of  the  context  within 
which  we  are  taking  it  —  the  laws  of  the  associative  con- 
text of  the  individual  mind ;  of  the  intersubjective  con- 
nections of  social  history ;  and  of  the  physical  uniformities 
as  observed  by  natural  science.  This  is  true,  though  they 
must  also  be  acknowledged  as  hanging  together  within  a 
dynamic  whole. 

We  can  see  now  that  the  contention  of  Bradley,  that  the 
object  selected  or  referred  to  in  the  truth  attitude  is  always 
reality,  is  at  best  a  clumsy  way  of  putting  it.  It  reminds 
one  of  the  story  of  the  man  in  the  Adirondacks  who  tried 
to  shoot  a  bear  by  aiming  at  him  generally.  To  be  sure, 
underlying  our  whole  search  for  knowledge  is  the  postulate 
that  the  facts  or  processes  which  we  strive  to  know  be- 
long to  one  world  with  our  cognitive  purposes  and  with 
each  other,  i.e.,  they  can  make  differences  to  each  other. 
A  wholly  indifferent  process  is  obviously  unknowable. 
But  while  this  postulate  of  continuity  is  assumed  or  tacitly 
implied  in  all  our  judgments,  it  can  hardly  be  said  to 
define  the  judging  process.  This  does  not  aim  at  the 
universe  generally,  but  is  fundamentally  selective.  The 
object  must  be  singled  out  from  the  immediate  mass  of 
experience  by  a  conscious  purpose  ;  it  becomes  meaning- 
ful precisely  by  being  thus  selected  and  furnished  its 
specific  context.  The  object  of  the  selective  meaning  is 


280  Truth  and  Reality 

precisely  what  the  subject  sets  itself  or  is  interested  in, 
whether  Apollo,  or  two  plus  two,  or  gravitation,  or  your 
friend's  opinion,  or  time,  or  space.  There  is  no  need  of 
mystification  here. 

That  all  the  facts  or  processes  of  the  universe  belong 
together  within  an  absolute  context  of  significance;  that 
every  process  makes  a  reflective  difference  to  every  other, 
or  is  a  fragment  which  dialectically  unravels  a  through  and 
through  meaningful  system  ;  and  that  therefore  in  meaning 
anything  whatsoever  we  cannot  help,  whether  we  know  it 
or  not,  to  mean  the  whole,  because  it  is  the  whole  that 
means  —  this,  while  a  logically  possible  hypothesis,  is  not 
a  self-evident  axiom.  It  does  not,  with  all  its  confidence, 
dispel  one  whit  of  our  ignorance  or  make  scientific  experi- 
ment and  discovery  any  less  indispensable.  It  must  at  any 
rate  come  as  an  induction  from  the  needs  of  human  experi- 
ence, not  as  an  assumption  at  the  outset. 

TIME   AND   THE   OBJECT   OF   TRUTH 

Is  the  object  either  a  past  or  future  state  of  conscious- 
ness ?  Can  the  object  in  the  first  place  be  stated  as  a  past 
state  of  consciousness  ?  This  has  been  assumed  by  many 
philosophers.  It  has  been  pointed  out  that  consciousness 
is  ever  on  the  wing  ;  that  to  attempt  to  analyze  and  describe 
it  is  to  transfix  it ;  and  that  what  reflection  deals  with, 
therefore,  is  something  that  has  been,  ^postmortem  autopsy. 
We  are  told  that  knowledge  looks  backward,  while  action 
looks  forward.  If  this  were  true,  we  could  not  only  not 
know  our  passing  moments,  we  could  know  no  object 
whatever,  as  every  object  of  knowledge  must  figure  in  this 
passing  stream.  To  be  sure,  the  reflective  attitude  is  very 
different  from  the  non-reflective,  and  an  immediate  content 


The  Object  and  its  Contexts  281 

may  later  figure  in  a  reflective  context.  But  subject  and 
object  cannot  be  separated  in  time ;  they  are  phases  or 
poles  of  the  same  reflective  moment.  The  object  in  any 
moment  is  what  we  mean,  that  which  interests  us,  that 
which  we  conceive  as  the  fulfillment  of  our  purposes 
whether  moving  or  static.  And  this  surely  need  not  be  a 
past  state  of  consciousness,  unless  the  purpose  is  to  under- 
stand the  past.  And  even  here  we  are  striving  to  realize 
at  least  an  individual,  and  generally  a  social,  present  pur- 
pose* —  a  purpose  big  with  the  future,  which  it  strives  to 
bring  to  birth. 

On  the  other  hand,  it  has  been  maintained  that  the  ob- 
ject must  be  stated  as  future  states  of  consciousness.  Truth, 
we  are  told,  consists  in  its  consequences.  As  attention  is 
essentially  prospective ;  as  knowledge  is  for  the  sake  of 
adjustment  to  a  larger  world,  this  view  seems  more  reason- 
able than  that  the  object  is  a  past  state  of  consciousness. 
But  while  the  future  consequences  may  furnish  a  corrective 
of  knowledge,  they  cannot  be  the  object  aimed  at.  If  the 
truth  attitude  consisted  in  consequences  altogether,  it  would 
be  as  meaningless  as  it  would  be  non-existent  We  must 
aim  at  a  present  constitution,  we  cannot  aim  at  what  does 
not  as  yet  exist.  Even  the  consequences  as  we  picture 
them  to  ourselves  are  our  ideal  constitution,  based  upon 
present  data,  the  projection  of  the  uniformities  as  we  must 
take  account  of  them.  In  the  process  of  experience,  to  be 
sure,  both  the  setting  and  the  values  may  change ;  and  the 
aim  comes  to  have  new  meaning,  whether  it  works  or  must 
be  abandoned.  But  the  object  referred  to  is  not  the 
future  consequences  with  their  unforeseen  real  differ- 
ences. They  constitute  quite  another  story,  which  must  be 
waited  for. 


282  Truth  and  Reality 

In  the  effort  to  arrive  at  truth,  history  and  science  must 
use  the  same  methods.  In  either  case,  we  must  proceed 
by  means  of  hypothesis  to  select  and  systematize  our  facts 
and  weave  them  into  a  consistent  whole.  In  either  case 
validity  must  mean  that  the  results  permit  of  social  agree- 
ment, as  the  process  of  investigation  goes  on.  The  data  of 
the  past  must  be  treated  as  the  data  of  the  present,  the 
motives  of  Caesar  like  those  of  Roosevelt,  the  past  nebulae 
like  present  nebulae.  In  either  case,  the  immediate  data 
must  be  reconstructed  into  a  whole  on  the  basis  of  their 
identities  and  differences,  interpreted  in  terms  of  concepts. 
Sometimes  we  may  simplify  our  present  complex  situation 
by  spreading  it  out  as  a  genetic  series,  as  Darwin  simpli- 
fied the  present  complex  forms  of  life  by  his  evolutionary 
theory.  Sometimes  we  may  simplify  past  results  by  re- 
producing them  in  present  experiments  as  physics  illus- 
trates geological  changes,  by  its  high  pressure,  its  electric 
furnaces  and  other  experiments.  But  whether  we  are  deal- 
ing with  scientific  or  historic  construction  we  are  striving 
alike  to  unify  present  data. 

The  difference  between  history  and  science  is  not  a 
methodological  difference,  but  a  metaphysical  difference. 
Science  is  dealing  with  a  world  which  we  acknowledge  as 
existent.  The  chemist  and  the  psychologist  can  become 
perceptually  continuous  with  the  objects  which  they  mean, 
while  the  historian  from  his  symbolic  data,  which  we  call 
records,  is  trying  to  reproduce  an  object  no  longer  possible 
of  perception  or  direct  communication.  Caesar  is  no  longer 
marching  his  legions  across  the  Rubicon ;  fair  Helen  and 
the  heroes  of  the  Trojan  war  are  at  rest.  To  be  sure,  the 
historian  is  not  dealing  with  a  myth  world  any  more  than 
the  scientist.  He  is  dealing  with  individual  meanings  or 


The  Object  and  its  Contexts  283 

structures  continuous  with  our  knowing  attitude.  But  these 
individuals  have  survived  only  through  the  symbolic  substi- 
tutes or  vehicles  of  language  and  art  which  have  carried  the 
meanings  down  the  stream  of  time.  The  parchment  has 
survived  the  creator  of  the  meaning,  though  the  soul  of  the 
meaning  itself  may  outlive  many  parchments,  may  require 
a  succession  of  carriers.  The  continuity  is  a  mediate  con- 
tinuity; and  a  mediate  continuity  which  only  leads  ideally 
back  to  the  real  subject.  The  real  processes  themselves, 
witl\  their  living  glow,  are  not  reversible  or  reproducible. 
The  time  element,  therefore,  makes  the  difference  between 
the  facts  which  the  scientist  and  the  historian  are  striving 
to  reach.  This  comes  in  as  a  limiting  or  metaphysical  con- 
cept, however,  and  does  not,  as  such,  play  a  part  in  the 
induction  which  must  depend  through  and  through  upon 
data,  whether  as  regards  content  or  chronology. 

Since  reality  is  individual  and  changing,  absolute  fact, 
as  our  final  interpretation  of  reality,  must  be  regarded  as 
a  conceptual  limit.  Fact,  as  we  have  it,  is  the  result  of 
such  identities  as  can  be  reached  by  various  coexisting 
meanings  about  their  common  intent,  as  regards  themselves, 
the  past  and  nature.  This  interpretation,  however,  is  an 
indefinite  quantity.  Our  interpretations  and  intents  must 
still  be  reinterpreted  to  fit  into  the  future  contexts  of  judg- 
ing experience.  The  context  of  history,  so  far  as  we  know, 
is  never  completed.  What  is  the  use  of  talking  of  the 
absolutely  abiding  and  permanent,  where  nothing  so  far  as 
we  know  is  abiding  or  permanent,  and  where  life  is  a  con- 
tinuous readjustment  to  a  changing  world  of  facts  and 
values?  On  the  other  hand,  what  is  the  use  of  talking 
about  an  absolute  flux  where,  after  all,  we  have  a  consider- 
able degree  of  continuity  and  steadiness  ?  Absolute  flux 


284  Truth  and  Reality 

and  absolute  identity  are  both  logical  limits  within  such  a 
world  as  ours.  Here  I  can  see  the  advantage  of  the  absolute 
as  an  ideal  hypothesis.  Absolute  fact  would  be  the  steady 
glare,  the  unblinking  insight,  of  an  absolute  ego,  the  same 
yesterday,  to-day  and  forever.  Such  a  limiting  concept, 
like  Newton's  absolute  rate  of  motion,  furnishes  at  least  a 
convenient  device  for  showing  the  relativity  of  our  actual 
facts,  as  Newton's  hypothesis  of  an  absolute  rate  of  motion 
shows  the  relativity  of  all  empirical  rates. 

One  thing,  however,  is  clear.  Truth  always  means  to 
be  eternal.  No  truth  ever  intended  its  own  falsity,  even 
though  our  knowledge  of  the  law  of  change  has  made  it 
evident  in  general  that  it  may  not  be  final.  In  so  far  as  it 
satisfies  our  demand,  is  really  truth  for  us,  there  is  stamped 
upon  it  its  own  eternal  intent.  I  have  reference  here  not 
to  the  mere  symbols  which  stare  us  in  the  face  with  their 
permanence  of  structure,  even  after  they  have,  like  old, 
worn-out  clothes,  been  discarded.  I  am  referring  to  the 
living  truth  attitude.  This  always  says,  "  Verweile  doch  ! 
Du  bist  so  schon."  Precisely  here  lies  the  tragedy  of 
truth.  The  real  world,  the  real  subject  that  judges  and 
the  real  object  it  means,  know  of  no  eternity;  they  will  not 
be  bound  by  the  chains  of  thought,  Parmenides  notwith- 
standing. Thus  our  experience  is  ever  outgrowing  our 
concepts,  crystallized  into  language.  Even  when  the  sub- 
jective structure  grows  stereotyped  and  is  satisfied  with 
the  old  point  of  view,  the  real  situation  does  not  stop  for 
all  that.  What  is  more  pitiable  than  to  see  the  old  investi- 
gator sticking  to  his  antiquated  hypothesis  in  spite  of  new 
evidence  and  larger  generalizations  ? 

Truth  or  meaning  is  always  of  the  moving  now.  It 
makes  sketches  by  catching  certain  constancies  —  sketches 


The  Object  and  its  Contexts  285 

something  like  reality,  even  as  the  cartoonist's  sketch  re- 
sembles Roosevelt  sufficiently  for  identification  —  but  the 
real  change  value  it  cannot  catch,  except  as  it  congeals 
into  results.  Truth,  therefore,  just  because  it  attempts  to 
fix  a  world  of  process,  must,  to  a  certain  extent,  be  hypo- 
thetical. It  cannot  bind  the  future.  It  is  based  upon 
the  relative  uniformities  of  experience  which  in  the  case  of 
the  physical  world  have  an  almost  eternal  fixity  as  com- 
pared to  our  fleeting  lives.  Outside  of  that,  our  equations 
talk  nonsense,  as  Clifford  says.  The  laws  of  science,  even 
mechanics,  are,  after  all,  our  plastic  attitudes  toward  things. 
Our  atoms  and  ethers,  our  law  of  conservation  of  energy 
and  our  law  of  gravitation,  must  be  retranslated  in  the 
light  of  fresh  discoveries.  The  very  fact  that  our  laws  are 
human  concepts,  apart  from  any  change  in  the  objects 
they  intend,  which  for  mechanical  purposes  may  be 
practically  stable,  must  make  them  plastic  in  the  ongoing 
stream  of  experience.  The  unity  we  find  in  things  is  first  of 
all  the  unity  of  our  experience  and  must  vary  in  meaning 
with  it. 

IS   TRUTH    CONVENTIONAL  ? 

Is  truth  conventional?  It  is  easy,  we  have  seen,  to 
confuse  truth  and  its  symbols,  such  as  language  and 
mathematical  models.  Those  who  have  insisted  upon  the 
conventional  character  of  truth  have,  no  doubt,  been  guilty 
of  such  confusion.  Because  language  is  made  up  of  abstract 
entities  in  the  way  of  substantives  and  relational  terms, 
they  have  insisted  that  our  judgments  also  are  made  up  of 
such  entities  and  hence  must  be  false  to  the  unitary  whole 
which  they  postulate.  Most  of  the  objections  raised  by 
such  critics  of  thought  as  Bradley  are  based  upon  the  con- 


286  Truth  and  Reality 

fusion  between  the  abstract  symbols,  thus  converted  into 
entities,  and  thought.  Hence  the  ease  with  which  thought 
is  transcended  in  those  writers  —  transcended  by  first  being 
caricatured,  and  then  abandoned  for  mysticism. 

But  it  is  not  only  from  the  side  of  philosophical  mysticism, 
but  from  mathematical  science  as  well,  that  the  question 
of  the  artificiality  of  truth  has  been  raised.  Nature  knows 
nothing  of  our  ellipses,  parabolas  or  equations.  Hence  is 
not  scientific  truth  merely  conventional  ?  No  doubt  there 
is  a  conventional  element  in  truth.  Human  nature  con- 
tributes the  measures  and  series,  the  descriptive  symbols ; 
and,  inasmuch  as  individual  invention  and  technique  count 
for  more  in  science  than  in  common  sense,  the  artificiality 
seems  all  the  greater.  But  it  must  be  recognized  that  there 
is  a  surd  of  content  which  we  do  not  invent,  viz.,  the  perceptual 
sequences  which  we  try  to  describe.  This  has  been  called 
"  the  universal  invariant."  The  psychologist  would  proba- 
bly be  skeptical  about  universal  invariants  where  human 
individuals  are  involved,  but  we  may  be  said  to  have  at 
least  such  constancy  as  permits  of  pointing,  and  which 
furnishes  the  real  currency  on  which  our  credit  system  in 
the  way  of  scientific  laws  and  formulae  do  business.  The 
contents  may  remain  constant,  however  much  their  values 
may  change  in  new  subjective  contexts. 

The  phenomenal  character  of  our  knowledge,  however, 
does  not  consist  in  that  facts  are  vitiated  by  being  known, 
as  has  sometimes  been  held.  On  the  contrary,  reality, 
whether  of  the  thing  kind  or  the  self  kind,  is  precisely 
what  we  must  take  it  as,  in  different  contexts.  Truth  is 
what  we  mean  as  we  systematically  strive  to  imitate  the 
intended  object.  What  makes  our  knowledge  so  phenome- 
nal and  instrumental  lies  in  what  it  must  omit,  rather  than 


The  Object  and  its  Contexts  287 

in  what  it  says.  Our  selection  is  not  adequate  to  the  rich- 
ness of  reality.  We  fail  to  exhaust  the  continuities  of 
nature  and  the  manifold  of  the  world  we  strive  to  share. 
And  while  our  conceptions  help  to  piece  out  our  percep- 
tions, still  our  results  are  proximate  and  pragmatic.  For  the 
purpose  of  prediction  and  practical  control,  we  emphasize 
the  common  and  uniform.  But  we  pay  dearly  for  our  in- 
variants in  omitting  the  fleeting  values  and  meanings  that 
give  each  moment  its  concreteness.  This  is  especially 
true  in  dealing  with  the  world  of  selves,  past  and  present. 
For  such  concreteness  we  substitute  our  averages,  our 
classificatory  systems,  our  space  and  time  series.  We 
split  the  universe  into  special  departments,  with  their  partial 
hypothesis,  to  meet  our  needs  and  limitations.  It  is  this 
selective  and  abstract  character  of  knowledge  that  makes 
it  seem  so  gray  compared  with  the  glow  of  life. 

Grau,  teurer  Freund,  ist  alle  Theorie 
Und  gnin  des  Lebens  goldner  Baum. 

But  it  is  also  this  that  makes  it  so  convenient  an  instru- 
ment in  finding  our  way  from  fact  to  fact  and  in  meeting 
the  complexity  of  life.  The  unique  and  individual  shades 
of  meaning,  the  fleeting  rainbow  hues  of  the  moment,  each 
will  must  acknowledge  or  supply  for  itself. 

What  meaning  we  are  justified  in  attributing  to  this 
acknowledged  reality  depends  upon  the  functional  agree- 
ment of  ideas  with  further  experience.  This  reading, 
however,  is  not  a  matter  of  our  observing  brain  changes, 
but  of  observing  conduct.  We  do  not,  unless  we  are  psy- 
chologists, consciously  watch  other  people's  bodily  symp- 
toms and  compare  them  with  our  own,  even  were  this 
possible.  Differential  reaction  goes  hand  in  hand  with 


288  Truth  and  Reality 

differential  meaning,  long  before  we  reflect.  Through  a 
long  process  of  survival  selection  and  through  social  imita- 
tion, we  have  come  to  react  spontaneously  upon  certain 
situations,  including  the  behavior  of  other  human  beings. 
In  higher  mind-relations,  this  means  an  immediate  inter- 
pretation of  language.  This  is  what  gives  the  intuitive 
character  to  all  our  normal  interpretation  of  other  selves. 
We  start  with  an  implied  hylozoistic  philosophy  of  the 
world,  which  we  afterward  individualize  through  experi- 
ence into  objects  with  more  or  less  definite  differential 
significance  —  the  world  of  selves  and  the  world  of  things, 
the  world  of  teleology  and  the  world  of  mechanism,  with 
their  specific  contexts. 

TRUTH   AND    METAPHYSICS 

The  persistent  effort  to  see  the  various  contexts  of  the 
world  of  objects  as  one  pattern,  the  divine  love  for  the 
wholeness  of  things,  we  call  metaphysics.  This  raises 
the  question  :  Is  metaphysics  a  science  ?  From  time  to  time 
the  controversy  breaks  out  as  to  whether  metaphysics  is 
science  or  poetry,  whether  it  deals  with  evidence  or  whether 
it  is  a  realm  of  free  imagination,  limited  only  by  its  own 
internal  purposes  and  the  law  of  consistency  in  working 
them  out.  If  one  looks  back  over  the  history  of  meta- 
physics, one  can  find  ample  reason  for  such  a  controversy. 
Metaphysics  has  too  often  attempted  to  spin  its  spider-web 
of  logic  from  its  own  a  priori  demands,  with  not  only  a 
neglect,  but  often  a  conscious  disdain,  for  facts.  History 
and  science  have  been  fitted  alike  into  the  philosopher's 
a  priori  models.  But  whatever  may  have  been  the  sins  of 
metaphysics  in  the  past  —  and  for  them  it  has  duly  suffered 
—  we  are  now  agreed  that  it  must  proceed  by  the  same 


The  Object  and  its  Contexts  289 

methods  as  science,  not  by  dogmatic  conviction,  but  by 
tentative  hypothesis  and  verification.  This  is  at  least  the 
import  of  the  pragmatic  movement.  It  differs  from  other 
sciences,  not  in  its  method,  but  in  its  intent,  in  the  prob- 
lems it  sets  itself,  viz.,  the  final  interpretation  of  knowledge 
and  the  other  overlapping  problems  of  experience,  which 
lie  outside  the  special  sciences. 

What  has  inspired  the  controversy  recently,  however, 
seems  to  be  not  a  question  of  method,  but  of  value.  It 
has  been  pointed  out  that  the  large  generalizations  of 
metaphysics  furnish  a  distinctly  esthetic  value  and  that 
this  is  the  characteristic  thing  about  them.  But  then  why 
is  not  all  science  a  branch  of  art  ?  It  is  a  long  time  since 
Plato  felt  the  kinship  of  truth  and  beauty  and  since  Lotze 
pointed  out  that  the  feeling  for  unity,  which  furnishes  the 
motive  and  joy  of  science,  is  an  esthetic  feeling.  However, 
while  we  recognize  identities,  we  must  not  neglect  differ- 
ences. No  doubt  science  and  esthetics  are  fundamentally 
the  same  in  their  instinctive  demands  for  unity,  distinct- 
ness and  simplicity.  But  the  limitations  which  are  recog- 
nized in  art  and  science  are  vastly  different.  We  do  not 
insist  that  art  shall  be  capable  of  verification  in  the  sense 
that  science  must  be.  The  former  must  minister  to  the 
instinct  for  the  beautiful,  and  must  do  so  by  eliminating 
the  accessories  and  selecting  the  relations  which  fit  that 
instinct,  while  science  must  deal  with  the  world  of  fact 
and  ascertain  its  constitution.  Both  are  selective.  Both 
idealize  their  world.  But  while  science  seeks  its  verifica- 
tion in  the  world  of  existence,  art  seeks  its  verification  in 
the  growing  meaning  and  unity  of  human  attitudes. 

Metaphysics  is  simply  the  attempt  to  find  out  the  truth 
about  reality  —  not  truth  for  a  certain  purpose  merely,  but 


290  Truth  and  Reality 

what  we  finally  must  think  about  our  world.  Reality  is 
non-communicative  sometimes,  like  a  man  who  refuses  to 
be  interviewed  —  well,  then  like  the  reporter,  we  have  to 
write  up  what  we  think  about  it  from  such  external  marks 
and  probabilities  as  we  can  find,  not  what  it  thinks.  In 
any  case,  philosophy,  like  the  enterprising  newspaper,  has 
to  get  out  a  good  many  editions  to  keep  up  with  the  pro- 
cession of  history. 


CHAPTER  XVI 
METAPHYSICS  —  THE  OVERLAPPING  PROBLEMS 

THAT  there  should  be  confusion  about  metaphysics  in 
the  popular  press  is  as  excusable  as  it  is  incurable.  No 
doubt  popular  opinion  has  its  implied  metaphysics,  too, 
but  its  ignorance  of  language  is  equal  to  its  ignorance  of 
science.  That  reputable  writers  on  science,  however, 
should  continue  to  use  metaphysics  as  a  name  for  the  oc- 
cult and  unknowable  on  the  one  hand  and  the  fictitious  on 
the  other,  would  be  unpardonable  except  for  their  neglected 
education.1  Such  misunderstandings  make  it  imperative 
on  the  man  who  has  the  courage  to  acknowledge  the  name 
of  Metaphysician — as  scorned  as  the  name,  Sophist,  of 
old  —  to  vindicate  his  field.  Alas,  he  must  do  this  not 
only  against  the  outside  world,  but  against  certain  flippant 
colleagues  of  his  own,  who  have  proven  false  to  their  own 
vocation. 


In  the  first  place,  I  want  to  correct  the  impression  that 
metaphysics  is  a  rare  out-of-the-way  thing,  which  only  a 
few  moss-grown,  more  or  less  fictitious  professors,  have. 
We  all  have  it.  Common  sense,  with  its  implied  dualism 

1  Two  otherwise  splendid  articles  in  the  Hibbert  Journal  illustrate  well  the 
above  confusion :  "  Atomic  Theories  and  Modern  Physics,"  July,  1909,  and 
"The  Metaphysical  Tendencies  of  Modern  Physics,"  July,  1910.  Both  by 
Professor  Louis  T.  More. 

291 


292  Truth  and  Reality 

or  materialism ;  the  agnostic,  with  his  hide-and-seek  game 
with  the  unknowable;  the  professed  scientist  with  his 
fundamental  assumptions  —  they  all  have  it  as  truly  as  the 
systematic  idealist  or  realist,  only  popular  metaphysics  is 
inconsistent  and  inarticulate. 

First  of  all,  let  us  define  what  we  mean  by  metaphysics 
and  metaphysical  entities.  Metaphysics  means  the  sys- 
tematic difference  that  facts  make  to  each  other  and  to  our 
reflective  procedure.  It  is  what  facts  must  be  taken  as  in 
the  entirety  of  our  experience  and  not  merely  for  a  con- 
ventional purpose.  For  the  purposes  of  prediction,  it  may 
be  convenient  to  reduce  time  to  space  units.  But  what 
does*  time  really  mean  in  relation  to  our  conduct  ?  Why  do 
we  have  to  take  account  of  it  at  all  ?  For  census  purposes, 
it  may  be  sufficient  to  take  people  as  numerical  units,  but 
what  are  they  really  in  relation  to  other  individuals  in  their 
endless  variety  of  social  contexts  ? 

If  we  must  assume  free  space  to  meet  the  facts,  then  free 
space  is  real.  And  it  has  the  properties  we  must  assume. 
Professor  L.  T.  More  says  :  "  Direct  evidence  shows  that 
kinetic  energy  is  propagated  through  what  experimentally 
must  be  regarded  as  empty  space.  This  energy,  called  heat 
and  light,  passes  to  the  earth  from  the  sun,  but  is  neither 
absorbed  or  otherwise  modified  until  ponderable  matter  is 
encountered."1  The  "infallible"  Michelsen  could  find  no 
difference  that  the  ether  makes  to  the  movement  of  the  earth. 
If  by  further  investigation,  science  finds  no  contrary  evi- 
dence, we  may  take  it  as  metaphysically  proven,  then,  that 
free  space  exists,  and  that  there  is  no  ether.  On  the  other 
hand,  to  show  that  for  certain  purposes  we  can  ignore  the 
existence  of  ether;  that  for  some  purposes,  we  can  treat  it 

i  Hibbert  Journal,  Vol.  VIII,  p.  816. 


Metaphysics —  The  Overlapping  Problems         293 

as  having  one  set  of  properties  and  for  another  a  different 
set  —  this  is  not  metaphysics.  We  cannot  believe  in  the 
existence  of  an  entity  for  one  purpose  and  not  believe  in  it 
for  another.  The  real  object  and  its  properties  do  not  vary 
with  our  cognitive  attitudes.  Such  description,  therefore, 
must  be  regarded  merely  as  a  convenient  symbolism.  Meta- 
physics does  not  mean  truth  for  a  certain  purpose.  It  means 
correlated  truth — truth  that  can  be  taken  as  the  same 
throughout  our  reflective  procedure.  However  convenient 
it  may  be  to  divide  our  problems,  there  is  not  one  truth, 
as  regards  the  same  objects,  for  chemistry  and  another  for 
physics.  Opposed  to  metaphysics,  then,  we  have  —  not 
science,  but  provisional  and  conflicting  sciences. 

Take  Huxley's  hypothesis,  so  current  in  recent  phys- 
iology and  psychology,  that  mind  is  an  epiphenomenon, 
i.e.t  not  an  energy  which  can  make  a  difference  to  other 
energies,  but  a  mere  chiaroscuro,  or  incidental  display  — 
the  head-light  of  the  engine,  which  indicates  the  move- 
ment but  does  not  make  it  go.  Now  such  a  theory,  if 
stated  as  the  truth  about  mind,  is  metaphysics,  however 
violently  anti-metaphysical  the  author  may  profess  to  be. 
Every  theory  must  be  tested  by  its  consistency  with  our 
total  experience,  past  and  present.  If  it  tallies  with  that, 
we  must  all  believe  in  it  for  the  time  being.  Unfortu- 
nately, this  theory  seems  to  be  based  on  certain  assump- 
tions rather  than  the  plain  facts  of  invariable  antecedence 
and  consequence  or  what  we  must  take  the  body-mind 
relation  as  being  in  experience.  According  to  the  impact 
theory  of  motion,  it  seemed  absurd  that  mind  —  ideas,  feel- 
ings, etc.,  should  push  the  elastic  balls  which  we  call  mole- 
cules. But  we  have  now  had  to  revise  our  impact  theory 
for  other  reasons  —  the  action  of  electricity,  for  example ; 


294  Truth  and  Reality 

and  so  the  imagination  no  longer  trips  itself  up  with  its 
own  pictures.  Such  a  theory  as  the  materialistic  theory 
of  mind,  therefore,  is  very  unmetaphysical.  It  may  be 
convenient  to  treat  mind  as  making  no  difference  for 
certain  purposes,  physiological  or  chemical,  but  it  does  not 
hold  in  the  larger  context  of  experience.  Ignoring  mind 
or  any  other  fact  as  a  convenience  for  a  certain  abstract 
purpose  is  not  anti-metaphysical.  It  simply  lies  outside  of 
metaphysics  as  the  systematic  truth  of  experience. 

Take  still  another  scientific  theory  of  the  last  generation, 
the  Darwinian  theory  of  the  origin  of  species,  as  based 
upon  accidental  variation  and  survival  struggle  without  the 
transmission  of  acquired  characters.  If  this  theory  really 
holds,  if  we  can  satisfactorily  meet  the  facts  of  life  that  way, 
then  it  is  a  metaphysical  theory.  If  we  simply  take  it  as 
a  convenient  hypothesis  for  biology,  which  leaves  chemical 
and  psychological  and  ethical  problems  still  in  abeyance,  if 
indeed  it  does  not  conflict  with  them,  then  it  is  provisional 
science  and  its  claim  must  be  held  in  the  balance  with 
other  claims  for  eventual  adjustment.  If,  as  some  biolo- 
gists have  come  to  feel,  it  is  inadequate  to  the  needs  of 
biology :  if  we  must  assume  a  formal  factor  in  evolution 
and  not  merely  accidental  variation;  or  if  we  must,  perhaps, 
assume  organic  memory  as  the  basis  of  cumulative  differ- 
ences —  if,  in  short,  the  hypothesis  fails  to  meet  the  in- 
tended facts  even  for  its  biological  purpose,  then  the 
hypothesis  is  unmetaphysical. 

Nor  does  metaphysics  have  any  more  sympathy  with 
dogmatic  and  irresponsible  agnosticism  than  with  spurious 
scientific  generalizations.  That  our  knowledge  is  very 
limited,  is  forced  upon  any  sane  man  by  experience. 
Relative  agnostics,  all  truth  seekers  must  be.  We  know 


Metaphysics  —  The  Overlapping  Problems         295 

only  in  part.  Therefore,  metaphysics  as  the  legatee  —  the 
clearing  house  of  the  special  sciences  — must  be  modest  and 
tentative.  But  in  so  far  as  we  can  proceed  systematically, 
on  the  basis  of  a  certain  theory,  it  is  really  true.  Reality 
conspires  with  us  for  the  truth.  It  is  not  a  lying  demon, 
bent  on  withholding  the  truth.  So  far  as  our  knowledge  is 
workable,  it  is  of  the  tissue  of  reality,  however  selected 
and  abstract  it  must  be  in  order  to  serve  the  needs  of  pre- 
diction and  life. 

To  speak  of  unknowable  forces  and  causes,  as  some  of 
our  colleagues  do  so  flippantly  and  with  such  an  air  of 
scientific  superiority,  is  as  unmetaphysical  as  it  is  unscien- 
tific. Metaphysics,  no  more  than  science,  is  concerned  with 
the  unknowable  or  occult.  It  postulates,  with  all  truth 
seeking,  that  truth  is  theoretically  possible,  and,  in  part 
at  least,  practically  attainable.  There  are  no  hidden 
essences  of  things.  Reality,  whether  mind  or  matter,  is 
what  we  must  take  it  as  in  the  systematic  procedure  of 
experience.  The  real  appears  for  just  what  it  is,  in  its 
various  relationships.  It  is  for  science  to  tabulate  these 
relationships,  and,  as  far  as  possible,  unify  our  expe- 
rience of  them  —  not  to  invent  superstitious  doubles  — 
always  keeping  in  mind  that  only  in  the  unity  of  the 
procedure  of  experience  does  the  real  truth  lie.  There  is 
no  truth  for  a  merely  split-off  purpose,  or  portion  of 
experience. 

We  are  not  ignorant  of  causes,  if  we  know  what  they  do. 
Electricity  is  just  what  it  shows  itself  as  being,  through  its 
operations,  under  definite  conditions.  To  say  that  we  know 
what  a  force  does,  that  we  can  tabulate  and  predict  its 
behavior,  and  yet  be  ignorant  of  its  character  is  a  contra- 
diction. It  is  the  gratuitous  inventing  of  a  hidden  essence 


296  Truth  and  Reality 

and  then,  by  definition,  asserting  that  we  can't  know  it. 
We  know  the  character  of  electricity  and  we  know  its 
transitions  when  we  know  its  conduct  under  stated  condi- 
tions. The  figment  of  certain  inscrutable  essences  or 
causes  survives  at  the  present  time  only  in  the  brains  of 
certain  physicists.  Metaphysics  learned  as  far  back  as 
Berkeley,  not  to  go  back  to  the  Middle  Ages,  that  assump- 
tions are  not  to  be  multiplied  and  that  hypotheses  which 
make  no  difference  to  the  procedure  of  experience  must  be 
eliminated. 

We  see  now  the  scope  and  function  of  metaphysics.  We 
see  that,  if  it  must  necessarily  wait  upon  the  special  sciences 
for  much  of  its  material,  they  do  their  work  only  poorly,  if 
they  neglect  it.  And  fly  it  as  they  may,  it  is  the  wings. 
It  consists  in  the  final  beliefs  and  attitudes  towards  our 
world,  no  matter  what  name  we  give  it.  That  it  must,  in 
large  part,  wait  upon  the  special  sciences ;  that  the  proper- 
ties and  relations  of  things,  as  well  as  of  minds,  can  only  be 
truly  ascertained  under  those  determinate  conditions  which 
the  special  sciences  investigate,  will  be  admitted  by  all. 
On  the  other  hand,  metaphysics,  as  itself  a  special  science, 
need  not  wait  until  the  other  sciences  complete  their 
task.  It  must  continually  criticize  and  clarify  their  over- 
lapping problems,  whether  this  is  done  by  the  specialist 
himself  or  by  another  party  who  goes  over  his  results. 
Moreover,  metaphysics  may  do  its  work  in  part  in  advance 
of  the  special  sciences.  It  is  the  oldest  of  the  sciences. 
The  interest  in  the  general  perspective  came  first  —  the 
overlapping  principles  which  the  Greeks  outlined  for  pretty 
much  all  the  sciences.  They  discovered  the  basic  presup- 
positions of  scientific  procedure  or  the  laws  of  logic ;  they 
discovered  the  general  postulates  of  the  physical  sciences, 


Metaphysics —  The  Overlapping  Problems         297 

such  as  the  conservation  of  mass,  property  and  motion  ;  the 
concept  of  equivalence,  etc.  They  discovered  the'concep- 
tion  of  proportional  variation  as  basic  in  chemistry,  however 
crude  the  four  elements  of  Empedocles.  They  discovered, 
too,  as  early  as  Anaximander,  the  concept  of  evolution  as 
based  upon  the  selective  adaptation  to  environment.  They 
discovered  the  laws  of  association  in  pyschology  and  or- 
ganized the  central  principles  of  ethics  and  politics  into 
sciences  —  all  on  the  slenderest  basis  of  scientific  observa- 
tion and  with  the  interest  of  the  metaphysician  uppermost, 
viz.,  the  interest  in  "  the  wholeness  of  things,  both  human 
and  divine,"  to  quote  from  the  divine  Plato. 

To  discover  the  reality  of  time,  it  is  not  necessary  to  be 
conversant  with  the  difference  it  makes  to  all  the  special 
problems  of  science,  once  we  grasp  its  real  difference  to 
conduct  in  any  concrete  domain  of  experience.  So  with 
the  significance  of  causality.  Causality  is  not  a  generaliza- 
tion from  all  possible  causes,  which  we  should  never  be 
able  to  have,  but  the  grasping  of  the  relation  to  our  will 
in  some  clear  and  distinct  instances.  Only  so  could  we 
have  specialists  in  metaphysics  itself. 

II 

In  metaphysics,  as  in  the  special  sciences,  we  must  use 
the  abstractive  method,  i.  e.t  we  must  single  out  the  signifi- 
cant leadings  as  regards  the  belonging  together  of  the 
large  masses  of  facts.  We  have  no  right  to  import,  in  an 
arbitrary  way,  our  own  constructions  into  reality  in  its 
wholeness  any  more  than  into  its  parts.  The  content  must 
first  be  abstracted  from  the  world  as  experienced  and  then 
tried  out  as  to  its  leading.  Our  hypotheses  must  be  sug- 
gested by  experience  and  must  dip  into  experience  again. 


298  Truth  and  Reality 

This  seems,  indeed,  to  have  been  the  aim,  on  the  whole, 
in  the  history  of  thought.  The  difficulty  has  been  that, 
whereas  the  characteristics  selected  were  supposed  to  have 
universal  leading  from  part  to  part  of  experience,  they 
could  only  serve  the  function  of  partial  leadings.  Thus 
the  mechanical  view  of  the  universe  has,  indeed,  a  real 
basis  in  experience.  Part  of  our  world  has  the  character- 
istics of  solidity  and  mass  and  appears  to  act  by  impact. 
The  objection  to  materialism  is  that  it  has  made  a  partial 
character  of  the  world  do  service  for  the  whole,  and  has 
thus  been  forced  to  do  violence  to  part  of  the  facts. 

Again,  the  idealistic  view  cannot  be  ruled  out  from  the 
universe  so  long  as  there  are  minds  which  feel  and  think, 
whether  these  be  animal,  human,  or  supra-human.  The 
only  question  that  can  be  raised  is  not  whether  mind  is 
real  when  it  is  conscious  of  itself  —  when  it  tries  to  invent 
theories  about  reality  —  but  whether  mind  is  a  universal 
attribute  of  reality  in  terms  of  which  all  reality  can  be 
read.  And  here  evidence  is  lacking.  So  with  the  other 
historic  controversies  about  knowledge  and  reality ;  they 
are  never  wrong  altogether.  Their  mistake  rather  lies  in 
trying  to  make  a  part-truth  do  for  the  whole. 

We  have  seen  that  metaphysics  deals  with  the  over- 
lapping generalities  or  unities  which  do  not  come  within 
the  provinces  of  the  special  sciences.  However  much  the 
superstitious  specialist  may  revile  "  metaphysics,"  there  is 
a  dialectic  in  the  world  as  experienced,  which  forces  us  out 
of  the  pockets  which  we  have  so  conveniently  made  and 
makes  us  take  account  of  the  facts  in  large  relations. 
This  is  noticeable  in  the  combination  of  labels  which  the  sci- 
ences have  been  forced  to  adopt,  such  as  physical  chemistry, 
physiological  chemistry,  psycho-physical  organisms,  etc. 


Metaphysics —  The  Overlapping  Problems         299 

It  is  seen,  however,  in  an  even  more  important  way,  in 
certain  large  tendencies  to  correlate  facts,  especially  as 
indicated  by  two  concepts,  viz.  energy  and  evolution.  By 
means  of  the  concept  of  energy  and  its  equivalences  it  has 
become  possible  to  string  the  whole  world  in  space  on  one 
string  and  thus  to  destroy  the  dogmatic  cleavage  which  in 
the  past  has  tended  to  isolate  facts  into  rigid  departments. 
Mind  makes  definite  differences  to  body ;  and  immaterial 
energy,  such  as  electricity,  to  material  or  mass  entities. 
Tljus  we  are  forced  to  recognize,  empirically  as  well  as 
a  priori,  the  wholeness  of  things  in  space. 

Not  less  remarkable  has  been  the  influence  of  that  other 
tendency,  the  evolutionistic.  Especially  since  the  impulse 
which  Darwin  gave  the  movement,  there  has  been  a  ten- 
dency for  our  dogmatic  verbal  divisions  to  dissolve  and  for 
continuity  of  process  to  take  the  place  of  abstract  isolation. 
Not  only  have  the  original  biological  species  been  shown 
to  be  a  part  of  the  same  process  of  growth  and  adaptation 
which  had  long  before  been  recognized  in  the  stellar  world ; 
but  intelligence,  too,  has  its  history ;  it  is  the  proper  out- 
come of  the  process  which  its  presence  serves  to  reveal  in 
its  true  light  —  a  process  which  uses  mechanism  as  a  tool 
in  realizing  its  immanent  end.  For  the  tree  of  universal 
evolution,  as  every  tree,  is  known  by  its  fruit.  To  take 
account  of  structures  and  values,  not  merely  as  in  natural 
history,  but  to  recognize  their  place  in  the  Jnward  flow  and 
movement  of  life,  which  is  ever  appropriating  the  past  and 
ever  pregnant  with  a  new  future;  which  carries  within 
itself  its  own  law  of  growth  —  this  consciousness  of  whole- 
ness in  time  is  what  distinguishes  metaphysics  from  the 
partial  tabulations  of  the  historical  sciences. 

What  metaphysics  thus  aims  at  is  a  larger  correlation  of 


3OO  Truth  and  Reality 

the  sequences  and  values  of  the  special  sciences.  What- 
ever is  truly  observed  about  the  special  facts  and  sequences 
remains  true.  Metaphysics  does  not  transform  the  ob- 
served facts  and  values,  but  gives  them  a  larger  setting, 
and  thus  enables  us  better  to  appreciate  their  significance. 
In  practical  use,  its  contribution  seems  small  compared 
with  the  special  sciences;  in  liberal  culture  it  far  outstrips 
them.  As  Aristotle  has  so  nobly  said  :  "  All  the  sciences, 
indeed,  are  more  necessary  than  this,  but  none  is  better."  1 
It  will  be  seen  now  that  I  thoroughly  disagree  with  Pro- 
fessor Miinsterberg  and  others  as  regards  the  relation  of 
the  sciences  to  metaphysics.  The  sciences  do  not  willfully 
falsify  the  facts  for  us,  by  a  purely  artificial  treatment,  in 
the  service  of  our  practical  interests.  They  do  not  merely 
decompose.  They  also  unify  and,  in  unifying,  imitate  the 
qualities  and  relations  of  reality.  Science,  so  long  as  it  is 
true  to  its  quest,  will  neither  decompose  nor  unify  further 
than  the  facts  dictate.  Partial  its  hypotheses  often  are,  and 
often  conflicting,  too.  But  the  aim  of  all  the  sciences  is 
the  cooperation  toward  a  unified  perspective  of  experience, 
the  discovery  of  how  we  must  take  our  facts  in  their  total  re- 
lationships. Hence,  their  fundamental  aim  is  metaphysical. 
So  far  as  they  go,  at  any  rate,  they  mean  to  discover  how 
we  must  take  our  world.  For  we  cannot  adjust  ourselves 
to  our  world  on  the  basis  of  arbitrary  symbols  or  pictures. 
These  are  serviceable,  if  at  all,  only  because  they  serve  to 
indicate  to  us  the  specific  procedure  of  reality  and  so  en- 
able us  to  regulate  our  conduct  accordingly.  The  con- 
stancies of  science  must  be  identities  taken  out  of  the 
matrix  of  changing  reality,  to  help  us  in  meeting  its  de- 
mands. Truth  is  not  falsification  ;  it  is  identification.  It 
1  "  Metaphysics,"  Book  I,  Ch.  II,  paragraph  10. 


Metaphysics — The  Overlapping  Problems         301 

is  because  we  can  recognize  the  character  of  nature  as  in 
some  respects  the  same  in  the  flux  of  situations,  that  we 
have  prediction  and  control. 

We  see  thus  that  our  theory  of  knowledge  and  our 
theory  of  reality  are  inextricably  inter-dependent.  For  we 
know  reality  only  as  the  differences,  quantitative  and  quali- 
tative, which  it  makes  to  our  systematic  conduct.  And, 
on  the  other  hand,  reality  is  precisely  what  we  must  take 
it  as,  in  our  systematic  experience,  whether  we  are  dealing 
with  things  or  selves,  facts  or  values.  Knowledge  is  but 
the  sorting  of  reality,  however  partial  and  abstract  such 
sorting  may  be.  Reality,  with  its  identities  and  differences, 
is  precisely  what  dictates  our  procedure  in  realizing  our 
will.  It  is  what  it  is  known  as,  in  so  far  as  our  knowledge 
is  thorough  and  systematic.  To  suppose  that  knowledge 
alters  the  character  of  reality  is  to  cut  ourselves  off  from 
all  access  to  it,  whether  scientific  or  metaphysical.  The 
much  talked  of  phenomenality  of  knowledge  is  merely  its 
partiality  —  its  impatience  and  failure  to  take  facts  in  their 
systematic  togetherness.  This,  however,  does  not  rob  the 
aspects,  truly  observed  and  described,  of  their  reality. 
The  assumption  that  the  outer  context  of  perception  is  less 
real  than  our  inner  context  of  appreciation  is  a  confusion 
of  existence  and  value.  It  is  in  the  inner  context  we  must 
seek  the  significance  of  reality,  but  not  necessarily  its 
existence. 

Ill 

In  conclusion,  what  are  some  of  the  types  of  overlapping 
problems  with  which  philosophy  must  deal  ?  There  are 
three  fundamental  types  of  such  problems :  the  problem 
of  knowledge ;  the  problem  of  existence,  or  what  sort  of 


3<D2  Truth  and  Reality 

beings  and  relations  there  are;  and  the  problems  of  value, 
or  what  internal  unity  such  facts  have.  It  is  to  the  last 
two  types  of  problems  that  we  ordinarily  give  the  name  of 
metaphysics.  With  the  overlapping  problems  of  knowl- 
edge we  have  already  dealt  in  the  preceding  chapters.  We 
have  dealt  with  the  genesis  of  the  intellectual  categories, 
with  the  psychological  and  formal  nature  of  truth,  with  the 
criterion  of  truth,  and  with  the  relation  of  truth  to  its 
object.  These  are  problems  with  which  the  special  sciences 
cannot  deal,  but  they  are,  nevertheless,  of  the  greatest  im- 
portance for  intelligent  scientific  inquiry.  It  is  not  an 
accident  that  most  of  the  names  of  the  special  sciences 
end  in  the  term  logic  or  knowledge.  Logic,  in  the  broad 
sense  of  a  theory  of  method  and  of  knowledge,  does  indeed 
overlap  all  of  them.  They  are  all  part  of  the  game  of 
truth  and  must  obey  the  rules  of  the  game  ;  the  limitations 
of  the  game  are  their  limitations.1 

There  are,  further,  the  problems  of  existence  and  the 
problems  of  value,  with  which  metaphysics,  as  a  science, 
deals.2  First,  what  final  types  of  being  must  we  acknowl- 
edge in  our  adjustments  to  the  world  as  experienced  ? 
What  stuff  are  things  made  of  ?  How  must  we  take  the 
world  of  processes  ? 

In  the  first  place,  experience  up  to  date  indicates  that  how- 
ever diverse  processes  may  be,  they  can  make  differences  to 
each  other.  Causality  does  not  require,  so  far  as  we  can 
see,  identity  of  stuff.  Electrical  processes  can  make  pre- 
dictable differences  to  mechanical  and  to  mental,  etc.  The 

1  For  a  brief  statement  of  the  problem  of  knowledge,  see  the  first 
part  of  the  next  chapter. 

2  I  may  say  that  the  fundamental  concepts  of  reality  which  I  shall 
mention  here  in  a  brief  and  dogmatic  fashion  are  dealt  with  at  length 
in  a  volume  entitled  "  A  Realistic  Universe,"  soon  to  appear. 


Metaphysics —  The  Overlapping  Problems         303 

ability  to  make  predictable  differences  we  call  energy.  So 
this  serves  as  a  convenient  name,  however  thin,  for  the 
whole  world  of  process.  These  energies  are  capable  of 
being  classified  into  classes  or  groups.  It  seems  that  we  can 
simplify  our  energies  into  three  of  these  —  the  mechanical 
energies,  involving  mass ;  electrical  energies,  including 
light  and  magnetism,  where  weight  and  mass  do  not  apply  ; 
and  conative  energies  or  the  differences  that  our  minds 
can  make  to  each  other  and  to  things.  Of  course  we  have 
attempts  at  still  further  simplification.  The  idealist  would 
reduce  all  processes  to  the  mind  type.  But  here  we  are 
confronted  by  the  lack  of  evidence  as  regards  the  simpler 
processes  of  the  world.  Some  physical  theorists,  again, 
would  reduce  all  mass  energies  to  the  electrical  type.  But 
even  J.  J.  Thom/son  has  recognized  the  impossibility  of  ac- 
counting for  all  of  mass  on  the  electrical  basis.  This  three- 
fold division,  therefore,  seems  a  convenient  halting  place 
for  science ;  and,  if  so,  for  metaphysics,  because  metaphysics, 
too,  must  follow  the  lead  of  induction.  It  cannot  make  its 
own  facts. 

With  the  problem  of  stuff  goes  the  problem  of  inter- 
action, for  we  know  stuff  only  by  the  differences  it  makes. 
If  metaphysics  has  not  solved  the  question  how  certain 
made-to-order  entities  can  influence  each  other,  how  me- 
chanical entities,  such  as  atoms  and  molecules  can  interact 
with  psychical  entities,  such  as  thoughts  and  feelings  and 
vice  versa,  how  material  entities  can  make  a  difference  to 
immaterial,  if  it  has  not  answered  our  ancient  questions 
about  motion,  it  has  done  what  is  better:  it  has  shown 
that  the  questions  are  mostly  useless,  and  that  the  absurdi- 
ties to  which  they  lead  are  due  to  our  concepts,  not  to  the 
irrational  procedure  of  reality.  It  is  not  for  us  to  dictate 


304  Truth  and  Reality 

to  reality  what  can  happen  or  how  it  can  act,  but  to  take 
account  of  the  differences  which  the  parts  of  reality  do 
make  to  each  other  under  definite  conditions.  And  if  our 
assumptions  make  such  differences  absurd,  then  we  must 
revise  our  assumptions.  The  invention  of  cleavages  and 
parallelisms  in  reality  to  correspond  with  the  discrepancies 
of  our  assumptions,  and  thus  ruling  nature's  seeming  con- 
tinuities out  of  court,  may  be  a  proof  of  ingenuity,  but  not 
of  scientific  sanity.  As  regards  the  external  interrelations 
of  the  parts,  as  well  as  regards  the  nature  of  their  stuff, 
they  are  precisely  what  they  must  be  taken  as  in  the  defi- 
nite situations  of  experience. 

As  regards  time,  another  overlapping  problem,  it  seems 
clear  that  we  cannot  reduce  it  to  quantitative  units.  These 
are  merely  tools  for  predicting  the  flow.  Time  must  be 
identified  with  the  variation  of  positions,  not  their  static 
relation.  While  there  is  a  high  degree  of  constancy  making 
prediction  to  a  large  extent  possible,  time  seems  to  introduce 
an  element  of  contingency  and  novelty,  requiring  fresh  ad- 
justment. At  least  that  is  true  for  our  finite  experience. 
In  any  case,  time  is  involved  in  the  moving  of  the  scenery, 
not  its  static  relations. 

As  regards  space,  I  would  agree  with  Ostwald  that  "  empty 
space  is  known  to  us  only  by  the  quantity  of  energy  neces- 
sary to  penetrate  it,  and  occupied  space  is  only  a  group  of 
various  energies."  But  in  either  case,  space  as  distance 
makes  a  positive  difference  to  the  interacting  energies. 
And  this  is  the  only  difference  space  makes.  Such  attri- 
butes as  free  mobility  and  absolute  conductivity  are  nega- 
tive. They  mean  the  absence  of  energetic  interference. 

It  seems  convenient  to  separate  consciousness  from  the 
energies  —  taking  consciousness  as  the  condition  of  aware- 


Metaphysics  —  The  Overlapping  Problems         305 

ness,  given  a  certain  complexity  of  structure,  physiological 
and  mental.  Consciousness  is  such  an  independent  varia- 
tion, if  we  must  thus  take  it  in  the  unification  of  our  expe- 
rience of  our  world. 

Finally,  we  have  the  problem  of  value.  The  human 
mind  is  so  constituted  that  it  cannot  stop  with  the  mere 
ceaseless  flux  in  time  or  the  mechanical  interaction  of  parts 
in  space.  It  asks  about  the  why  and  the  whither.  Even 
Heraclitus  sought  for  a  law  of  change,  an  inner  unity 
running  through  the  scattered  parts  of  experience,  guiding 
the  play  of  chance.  And  while  we  cannot  regard  this 
unity  as  superimposed  mechanically  from  without,  as  in 
the  case  of  Paley's  watchmaking  god,  nor  regard  nature 
as  working  with  a  definite  model  in  mind,  according  to  the 
superficial  interpretation  of  final  causes,  yet  we  must  be- 
lieve that  the  universe,  somehow,  is  to  be  judged  by  its 
outcome  and  that  those  ideals  of  self-criticism  and  appreci- 
ation which  the  universe  in  its  more  developed  stages  holds 
up  to  itself  are  not  accidents,  but  in  the  deepest  sense 
nature's  self-realization,  that  liberation  which  is  dumbly 
striven  for  —  the  guiding  impulse  of  the  long  groping  his- 
tory of  evolution  with  its  repeated  trials,  failures,  and  fixa- 
tion of  types. 

We  must  recognize  that  the  universe  has  form  or  signifi- 
cant connection ;  that  its  processes  do  not  happen  by  mere 
accident;  that  evolution  is  not  bare  chance,  for  if  there  is 
no  form  or  order  in  reality,  our  own  reasoning  about  it  will 
be  irrelevant.  Therefore,  to  attempt  to  reason  or  to  have 
science  becomes  contradictory.  It  would  seem  strange,  too, 
that  reality  should  develop  these  formal  demands,  if  they 
are  not  somehow  germane  to  it  and  selective  in  its 
evolution. 


306  Truth  and  Reality 

These  are  suggestions  merely ;  only  some  of  the  many 
overlapping  problems.  Moreover,  all  the  investigations 
of  the  special  sciences  as  regards  the  specific  procedure  of 
reality  increase  our  metaphysical  knowledge.  For  meta- 
physics is  only  knowing  consistently  and  truly  the  relation 
of  our  objects  to  our  conduct.  The  qualities  of  things  as 
well  as  their  existence  are  known  through  the  differences 
they  make  to  the  systematic  procedure  of  human  nature. 
Speculations  outside  of  that,  whether  concerned  with  the 
natural  or  supernatural,  are  not  metaphysics  —  they  are 
nonsense. 


CHAPTER  XVII 
THE  REALITY  OF  RELIGIOUS  IDEALS 

NOT  the  least  significant  fact  of  this  great  scientific  age 
is  its  deep  interest  in  religion.  On  the  one  hand,  in  spite 
of  serious  protests  from  the  conservatives,  science  has  es- 
tablished its  right  to  apply  the  same  method  to  the  study 
of  religion  which  has  been  of  such  great  service  in  reducing 
the  facts  of  other  fields  from  chaos  to  order ;  and  thus  we 
have  Comparative  Religion,  Higher  Criticism  and  the 
Psychology  of  Religion.  On  the  other  hand,  attempts  have 
been  made  from  the  philosophical  side  to  furnish  the  same 
rationale  for  the  ultimate  religious  concepts  as  for  the 
scientific.  The  import  of  this  has  been,  not  to  show 
that  both  sorts  of  ideas  are  ultimately  equally  invalid, 
equally  lose  themselves  in  the  unknowable,  as  in  the  dark 
all  cows  are  gray ;  but  to  show  the  legitimacy  and  impor- 
tance of  both  in  steering  us  in  the  direction  of  the  real. 
What  I  am  concerned  with  in  this  chapter  is  to  inquire  into 
the  validity  of  our  religious  ideals;  but  to  do  this  I  shall 
have  to  inquire  first  how  any  ideals  become  valid.  If  this 
seems  a  roundabout  way,  I  still  feel  that  it  is  the  shortest 
way  to  reach  the  end  in  view. 


The  final  problem  which  any  theory  of  knowledge  must 
attempt  to  solve  is :  How  can  ideas  or  concepts,  which  are 
merely  structures  of  my  mind,  modifications  of  my  brain 

307 


308  Truth  and  Reality 

and  carried  about  in  my  head,  mean  or  express  the  real 
nature  of  the  world  ?  To  do  justice  to  this  problem  here 
would  be  to  furnish  a  complete  system  of  epistemology 
and  metaphysics.  The  limitation  of  our  task  makes  this 
impossible ;  at  most  we  can  furnish  only  mere  suggestions. 
We  are  concerned  with  the  problem  of  knowledge  in  gen- 
eral only  so  far  as  this  is  involved  in  our  more  specific 
problem,  namely,  the  real  basis  of  our  religious  ideals. 
The  first  question,  then,  which  we  shall  attempt  to  answer 
in  barest  outline  is :  How  do  concepts,  structures  in  our 
mind,  crystallize  or  thicken  into  being,  become  objective 
fact  ?  And  the  second,  more  special  one,  is  :  How  does 
the  criterion  of  the  objectivity  of  concepts  in  general  apply 
to  the  religious  ideals  ? 

One  of  the  most  suggestive  things  in  modern  philosophy 
is  Herbert  Spencer's  definition  of  life,  as  "  the  continuous 
adjustment  of  internal  relations  to  external  relations."  "  We 
perceive  that  what  we  call  intelligence  shows  itself  when 
the  external  relations  to  which  the  internal  ones  are  adjusted 
begin  to  be  numerous,  complex,  and  remote  in  time  or 
space ;  that  every  advance  in  intelligence  essentially  con- 
sists in  the  establishment  of  more  varied,  more  complete 
and  more  involved  adjustments ;  and  that  even  the  highest 
achievements  of  science  are  resolvable  into  mental  relations 
of  coexistence  and  sequence,  so  coordinated  as  exactly  to 
tally  with  certain  relations  of  coexistence  and  sequence  that 
occur  externally."  And  again  :  "  Any  assumption  is  justi- 
fied by  ascertaining  that  all  the  conclusions  deducible  from  it 
correspond  with  the  facts  as  directly  observed ;  by  showing 
the  agreement  between  the  experiences  it  leads  us  to  an- 
ticipate and  the  actual  experiences."  1  Or,  as  Professor 

1  "  First  Principles,"  Ch.  IV,  "  The  Relativity  of  Knowledge." 


The  Reality  of  Religious  Ideals  309 

James  would  express  it :  Our  ideas  are  valid  when  they  are 
"  coterminous  "  with  perception  or  fact  Our  idea  of  an 
eclipse  is  true  when  our  anticipation  of  it  in  space  and  time 
ends  in  the  facts  of  the  eclipse. 

Life  and  knowledge  are  essentially  adjustments  to  a 
larger  world.  The  springs  for  such  a  process  of  adjust- 
ment must  be  found  in  human  nature.  Modern  philosophy 
and  psychology  alike  emphasize  that  we  are  essentially 
active  or  willing  beings,  beings  with  desires  to  be  satisfied ; 
and  we  are  dependent  upon  the  environment  for  the  satis- 
faction of  those  desires.  Our  impulses  or  affections,  as 
Butler  pointed  out  long  before  Darwin  and  Spencer,  are 
centrifugal;  they  point  to  objects  beyond  themselves  for 
their  realization ;  human  nature  as  such  is  fragmentary, 
and  points  to  a  larger  world  for  completion.  Only  in  so 
far  as  the  smaller  system  is  adjusted  to  the  larger  system 
can  our  desires  be  realized.  But  how  can  the  smaller 
system  ever  know  anything  about  the  larger  and  thus 
properly  adjust  itself? 

The  English  empiricists  from  Locke  down  are  right  in 
emphasizing  that  our  adjustments  are  the  results  of  expe- 
rience. Our  instinctive  tendencies  would  remain  at  best 
vague  and  inchoate  if  it  were  not  for  individual  experience, 
which  serves  to  make  them  definite.  It  is  by  continuous 
attempts  at  adjustments,  the  fruitful  adjustments  surviving 
as  exciting  interest  or  gratifying  desire  while  the  vain  ones 
perish,  that  the  organism  learns  gradually  what  are  the 
proper  adjustments.  It  is  only  on  the  level  of  our 
ideational  adjustments,  however,  that  the  question  of  the 
true  and  the  false  arises.  The  fruitfulness  of  these  idea- 
tional adjustments  is  one  evidence,  at  least,  for  their  truth- 
fulness. While  not  all  fruitful  ideas  are  true  and  not  all 


3IO  Truth  and  Reality 

true  ideas  are  useful,  in  the  long  run  such  fruitful  adjust- 
ments must  be  true  to  the  character  of  reality.  If  decep- 
tion and  illusion  worked  as  well  in  the  long  run  as  truth, 
science  would  be  in  vain;  for  falsehood  is  infinite,  and 
there  can  be  no  science  of  falsehood.  The  usefulness  of 
deception  must  always  be  for  a  limited  purpose,  due  to  the 
imperfect  development  or  pathological  condition  of  human 
nature.  Just  as,  on  the  whole,  pleasant  things  are  whole- 
some, so,  on  the  whole,  useful  ideas  are  true,  though  in 
either  case  there  are  temporary  exceptions  in  the  evolu- 
tionary process;  in  either  case  we  must  supplement  ex- 
perience with  further  experience. 

What  the  early  English  empiricists  neglected,  in  their 
eagerness  to  show  that  we  learn  by  experience,  was  to 
answer  the  question :  Who  am  I  ?  —  to  define  the  individual. 
They  emphasized  the  part  played  by  the  environment  at 
the  expense  of  the  individual,  his  tendencies  and  needs. 
The  ego  was  to  be  a  mere  passive  tablet,  a  piece  of  white 
paper,  upon  which  Nature  could  write  her  sequences. 
This  implied  that  the  ego  must  be  a  mere  nothing  in  fact, 
as  Hume  points  out,  a  mere  result  of  association,  a  "bundle 
of  perceptions."  But  in  that  case  there  was  neither  any 
need  nor  any  possibility  of  adjustment  or  knowledge.  If 
the  individual  centers  are  nothing,  we  have  a  lot  of  nothings 
playing  on  nothings,  and  the  environment  has  vanished 
with  the  individual.  Thus  Humean  empiricism  would 
reach  its  logical  bankruptcy. 

It  was  at  this  point  that  Kant  took  up  the  problem. 
Kant  emphasized  the  dignity  of  the  individual  at  the  ex- 
pense of  the  environment.  The  mass  of  sensations  or  data 
which  are  thrust  upon  us  could  present  no  order  or  mean- 
ing as  such.  The  laws  and  system  of  the  data  are  the 


The  Reality  of  Religious  Ideals  3 1 1 

work  of  the  subject,  which  confronts  the  environment  with 
certain  predispositions,  certain  ways  of  looking  at  things. 
It  is  a  matter  of  wonder  to  the  naive  Kant  that  the  data 
conform  so  obediently  to  the  order  forced  upon  them  !  For 
we  make  the  system  of  nature.  What  makes  nature  seem 
so  objective  is  that  we  all  agree  in  making  it  in  the  same 
way ;  it  is  a  sort  of  social  collusion.  But  the  environment 
takes  revenge  for  this  violence  upon  it.  If  we  insist  upon 
making  Nature  according  to  our  models,  she  will  refuse,  at 
any  rate,  to  tell  us  anything  about  herself,  and  thus  leave 
us  to  the  solitude  of  our  own  fancies.  When  Kant  attempts 
to  distinguish  between  empirical  causal  relations  and  caus- 
ality in  general  as  dictated  by  the  subject,  his  system  utterly 
breaks  down.  If  particular  causal  relations  must  be  ascer- 
tained through  experience,  what  remains  for  the  boasted 
category  of  causality  to  do  ?  Thus  Kant,  in  giving  arbitrary 
priority  to  the  individual  subject,  lost  all  real  access  to  the 
environment. 

In  this  dilemma  the  theory  of  knowledge  remained  sub- 
stantially until  the  evolutionary  movement  Both  Hume 
and  Kant  emphasized  important  aspects  of  knowledge  :  we 
must  learn  from  experience  the  real  character  of  nature ; 
and  yet  we  can  only  get  out  of  nature  the  meanings  or  laws 
with  which  we  confront  it.  The  abstract  methods  of  Hume 
and  Kant  could  not  overcome  this  antinomy.  Both  neg- 
lected the  problem  of  the  genesis  of  knowledge,  in  the 
light  of  which  its  nature  must  be  interpreted.  The  two  po- 
sitions can  be  reconciled  only  in  a  more  concrete  theory  of 
the  individual,  which  takes  account  of  the  nature  of  the 
individual  as  modified  by  history. 

This  history  is  as  old  as  the  universe  in  its  changes  of 
cosmic  weather — for  old  as  star-dust  is  mind-stuff,  old  as 


312  Truth  and  Reality 

existence  are  ideals.  True,  we  have  no  right  to  read  the 
meaning  of  the  later  and  more  complex  stages  of  history 
into  the  earlier  and  simpler  ones  and  speak  of  inorganic 
nature  in  terms  of  will  or  reason,  as  animistic  philosophers 
are  fond  of  doing.  It  is  to  us,  the  spectators,  that  the 
simpler  stages  have  meaning  or  purpose.  Yet  we  believe 
that  the  simpler  ones  are  continuous  in  one  history  with  the 
more  complex  ones,  that  the  whole  process  is  obedient  to 
one  direction ;  and  though  we  cannot  reproduce  even  prob- 
lematically the  content  or  meaning  of  the  simpler  stages, 
we  can  at  any  rate  to  some  extent  reproduce  their  external 
or  phenomenal  form.  What  we  must  emphasize  is  that  we, 
as  thus  conditioned  by  race  history,  are  subjects,  conscious 
egos,  possessing  properties  of  our  own,  capable  of  certain 
habits  or  adjustments  as  regards  the  environment,  and  not 
the  mere  passive  result  of  mechanical  laws,  a  chance  con- 
junction in  the  dance  of  atomic  elements,  whether  sensa- 
tional or  material. 

When  the  individual  history  of  human  organisms  begins, 
a  certain  structural  differentiation,  as  a  result  of  the  survi- 
val process  of  evolution,  has  already  determined  for  us  our 
general  data  of  a  world.  Our  sense-organs  admit  only  of 
a  certain  kind  of  diversity ;  they  are  tools  for  picking  out  a 
certain  range  of  data  as  "  signs  "  of  the  energies  of  our  en- 
vironment. Not  only  our  data,  however,  but  our  capacity 
for  reacting,  both  in  general  and  in  more  specific  directions, 
has  already  been  determined  by  the  character  of  the  ner- 
vous system.  We  start  upon  our  brief  human  history  with 
a  certain  temperament  and  endowment ;  but  more  than  that 
we  possess  an  equipment  of  certain  dispositions  or  tenden- 
cies, needs  or  demands,  which  must  be  satisfied.  In  these 
we  reap  the  results  of  past  adjustments  from  a  race  history 


The  Reality  of  Religious  Ideals  313 

indefinitely  old.  And  while  these  results  are  not  experience, 
not  innate  ideas,  they  serve  to  economize  experience.  They 
furnish  us  with  the  warp  for  which  individual  experience 
must  furnish  the  woof.  They  are  general  docilities  which 
can  be  made  definite  by  being  consciously  tried  out 

These  tendencies  may  be  merely  individual  and  material, 
such  as  the  tendency  to  self-preservation,  characteristic  of 
all  life,  and,  we  might  say  with  Spinoza,  of  physical  things, 
too.  Or  the  tendencies  may  lead  to  social  satisfaction. 
They  may  be  a  craving  for  friendship,  a  taste  for  music,  a 
feeling  for  consistency,  a  sense  of  right,  or  a  yearning  for 
the  supernatural.  The  special  adjustments  or  tools  for  the 
satisfaction  of  these  tendencies  have  already  to  a  large  ex- 
tent been  provided  for  by  the  order  of  things  into  which  we 
are  born.  By  our  tendency  to  imitate  we  become  familiar 
with  the  adjustments  of  society,  its  knives  and  forks,  its  laws, 
its  science,  its  religion.  In  the  course  of  this  imitation 
which  we  call  education,  we  discover  our  own  meaning  or 
purpose — ourselves.  We  contribute  our  own  reaction  or  in- 
terpretation to  the  past.  But  whether  our  adjustments  are 
the  result  of  inherited  dispositions,  or  of  imitation,  or  of 
purposive  experiment,  what  determines  the  repetition  or 
survival  of  an  adjustment  is  its  capacity  for  ministering  to 
the  needs  of  the  individual  and  the  race. 

How  far  our  adjustments  or  dispositions  are  a  priori,  in  the 
sense  of  inherited,  or  are  acquired  within  the  history  of  the 
individual  organism,  we  are  not  at  present  in  a  position  to 
state,  and  perhaps  never  shall  know ;  but  one  thing  is  certain, 
when  we  begin  to  be  conscious  of  what  we  are  doing,  to  reflect 
upon  our  own  acts  and  processes,  we  do  find  ready-made  a 
complex  set  of  adjustments  or  dispositions ;  experience  has 
already  taken  on  certain  forms  or  serial  arrangements ;  we 


314  Truth  and  Reality 

look  for  certain  connections  and  continuities  between  phe- 
nomena. Hence  the  a  priori  categories  of  men  like  Kant 
and  Schopenhauer.  We  awaken  to  that  yearning  for  the 
wholeness  of  things  which  intoxicated  Plato ;  we  recognize 
certain  demands  for  consistency  and  beauty,  which  both 
outstrip  and  set  the  program  for  individual  striving. 
That  these  adjustments  or  dispositions  are  the  products  of 
the  interaction  of  the  organism  and  the  environment,  phys- 
ical and  ideal,  through  the  history  of  the  race ;  that  the 
environment  has  dictated  to  us  what  dispositions  we  must 
entertain  to  survive,  long  before  our  dispositions  begin  re- 
flectively to  dictate  to  nature  what  it  shall  mean  —  this  is 
the  contribution  of  the  evolutionist  movement.  To  sup- 
plement the  empiricism  of  Locke  and  Hume,  therefore, 
we  must  first  recognize  an  instinctive  structure  with  its 
tendencies,  a  subject  capable  of  cumulative  adjustment, 
and  then  substitute  for  the  history  of  one  individual  ex- 
perience the  history  of  the  race.  In  order  to  learn  from 
experience,  we  must  be  equipped  with  mines  of  tendencies 
or  interests  which  the  energies  outside  us  can  touch  off. 
Nature  can  only  become  real  to  us  by  passing  through 
human  nature. 

In  all  our  adjustments,  whether  they  are  self-conscious 
or  merely  sentient,  is  involved  trial,  or  experiment. 
Knowledge,  too,  starts  with  certain  guesses,  certain  random 
efforts,  spontaneous  constructions  —  those  surviving,  on 
the  whole,  which  issue  in  fruitful  results.  And  the  results 
become  fruitful  because  the  adjustments  are  made  with 
reference  to  the  character  of  reality.  The  organism  must 
take  account  of  the  diversity,  as  well  as  identity,  of  the 
environment;  in  other  words,  for  the  mental  adjustment 
to  become  fact  or  to  be  successful,  the  meant  identity  or 


The  Reality  of  Religious  Ideals  3 1 5 

meant  diversity  must  coincide  with  the  objective  identity 
or  diversity  of  character.  This  aim  at  adjustment  may 
be  found  in  all  stages,  and  may  take  account  of  a  very 
abstract  and  immediate  aspect  of  the  environment  or  may 
aim  at  a  very  concrete  and  remote  environment.  Nor  can 
we  be  neutral  as  regards  reality  beyond  us,  as  we  might 
be  if  we  were  merely  bundles  of  perception  or  logic  ma- 
chines. We  are  bundles,  not  of  perceptions,  but  of  desires. 
The  necessity  to  act  in  order  to  survive  makes  it  impossible 
to  ,be  indifferent  as  regards  our  environment.  And  our 
actions  imply  certain  beliefs  with  reference  to  the  bigger 
world  —  the  environment  which  we  confront,  whether  we 
are  conscious  of  those  beliefs  and  whether  they  are  those 
we  profess  or  not. 

How  can  we  bring  these  beliefs  or  hypotheses  to  the 
test  ?  How  can  we  know  whether  they  are  the  mere  con- 
structions of  our  brain,  mere  symbols,  or  whether  they  also 
express  the  character  of  reality  ?  We  have  two  ways  of 
testing :  one  is  a  subjective  way,  referring  to  the  proper 
functioning  of  our  own  thought;  the  other  is  objective,  or 
refers  to  action.  Ultimately,  the  two  must  coincide.  The 
subjective  criterion  is  that  of  consistency.  Contradictory 
judgments  cannot  both  be  true.  If  I  make  the  judgments 
that  a  house  is  red  and  that  it  is  not  red  in  the  same  respect, 
both  judgments  cannot  express  fact.  But  mere  consistency 
does  not  make  our  ideas  objective.  Nor  is  social  agreement 
sufficient  to  constitute  objective  fact.  We  can  agree  as  to 
the  meaning  of  centaurs  and  mermaids  and  a  geometry  of 
«  dimensions.  Yet  this  agreement  does  not  constitute  them 
objective  facts.  Ideas  to  become  objective  must  not  merely 
be  consistent  and  capable  of  being  agreed  upon  :  they  must 
lead  to  certain  consequences  of  perception  and  action.  If 


316  Truth  and  Reality 

we  can  act  as  if  a  certain  faith  is  real,  if  the  environment  re- 
sponds to  our  action  by  ratifying  our  will,  then  our  faith  crys- 
tallizes into  being  and  ceases  to  be  mere  faith  or  subjective 
attitude.  We  have  hit  upon  the  meaning,  the  real  character, 
of  our  environment.  Hence  our  environment  responds  by 
granting  our  request.  Truth,  finally,  must  be  tested  through 
the  consequences  in  the  way  of  conduct  or  procedure  to 
which  it  leads  —  provided  that  we  include  in  these  both  the 
difference  which  the  object  makes  to  our  individual  nature 
now  and  the  ratification  of  further  experience,  the  latter 
coming  in  only  as  a  proviso,  necessary  at  any  one  time, 
owing  to  the  finitude  of  human  nature  and  the  fluent  char- 
acter of  reality.  True,  sometimes  our  response  takes  the 
form  of  intuitive  certainty,  the  net  result  of  race  history ; 
but  this  certainty  must  in  the  end  be  capable  of  being  tested 
in  the  procedure  of  experience  —  even  the  golden  rule  and 
the  venerable  axioms  of  geometry. 

In  the  degree,  then,  in  which  we  can  act  as  if>  we  have 
hit  upon  the  true  meaning  of  the  environment;  we  can 
dictate  to  it  because  it  has  already  dictated  to  us.  Most  of 
our  guesses  or  faiths  as  regards  reality  are  only  partially 
responded  to ;  we  can  only  in  part  act  as  if.  We  can  only 
act,  perhaps,  as  though  our  faith  were  real  for  a  certain 
abstract  purpose.  However,  in  so  far  as  the  environment 
responds  even  for  the  abstractest  purpose,  our  idea  or  faith 
must  embody  an  essential  aspect  of  reality.  Thus  the 
atomic  theory  serves  admirably  for  the  grosser  purposes 
of  chemistry,  while,  in  its  classic  form  at  least,  it  breaks 
down  for  certain  phenomena  of  physics,  such  as  electricity. 
Hence  its  truth  must  be  regarded  as  partial.  It  does  not 
express  the  whole  truth  of  the  character  of  the  physical 
world  ;  yet  it  does  embody  an  essential,  if  abstract,  aspect 


The  Reality  of  Religious  Ideals  317 

just  in  so  far  as  we  can  act  as  if  the  world  were  made  that 
way  and  get  our  results.  If  we  take  the  ether,  again,  we 
find  that  for  certain  purposes  it  has  been  treated  as  a  per- 
fect fluid  and  for  others  as  a  perfect  jelly.  We  have  here 
apparent  contradiction  in  the  assumed  substrate  of  phe- 
nomena, yet  both  beliefs  with  reference  to  it  lead  to  fruitful 
consequences.  Hence  the  abstract  partial  aspects  must 
each  have  its  right ;  and  a  concept  must  be  possible  that 
embodies  both  characters  without  contradiction.  When  we 
can  form  a  concept,  a  mental  construction,  on  which  we 
can  act  consistently  as  if  it  expressed  the  essence  or  nature 
of  reality,  then  this  ceases  to  be  mere  belief  or  idea;  it 
thickens  into  being,  it  is  reality.  Reality  then  conforms 
to  our  categories  or  ideas  because  these  have  been  adjusted 
to  it  It  should  be  added  that  knowledge  becomes  ex- 
haustive only  when  we  deal  with  objects  which  are  them- 
selves meanings.  Any  number  of  people  can  have  the 
reality  of  Hamlet. 

It  has  been  fashionable  of  late  to  speak  of  concepts  as 
shorthand,  merely  convenient  symbols,  but  without  relation 
to  the  real  world.  In  so  far  as  they  are  mere  subjective 
guesses,  and  reality  refuses  to  respond  to  them,  to  behave 
as  if  they  were  true,  in  so  far  we  may  speak  of  them  as 
mere  shorthand,  mere  symbols.  But  in  so  far  as  they 
become  convenient,  in  so  far  as  they  form  the  basis  of 
prediction,  just  so  far  do  they  cease  to  be  mere  shorthand. 
They  must  seize  upon  characters  of  reality  in  order  to  be 
serviceable,  even  though  in  the  case  of  physical  nature 
these  characters  are  to-us-ward  and  do  not  reproduce  or 
copy  the  inner  reality  of  the  process,  and  so  do  not  com- 
pletely thicken  into  being,  but  must  be  regarded  as  instru- 
mental—  good  instruments  if  they  work.  So  far  as  regards 


318  Truth  and  Reality 

the  real  or  inner  nature  of  the  environment,  we  must  act 
by  faith,  not  by  sight.  Our  sensations  as  such  are  depend- 
ent for  their  character  not  merely  upon  the  environment, 
but  also  upon  our  psycho-physical  organism,  and  at  best 
they  are  but  signs  of  what  we  intend.  Nor  can  the  real 
character  of  the  environment  be  ascertained  by  mere 
thought,  as  Plato  supposed,  but  by  thought  or  creative  im- 
agination that  realizes  itself  in  action.  Our  ultimate  clew 
to  reality  is  that  it  behaves  as  if  it  conformed  to  our  idea 
of  it;  when  that  happens,  our  constructive  imagination 
must  have  succeeded  in  divining  it  or  hitting  it  off,  or  suc- 
ceeded so  far  as  our  finite  limitations  permit.  How  com- 
plex this  environment  shall  be  assumed  to  be,  what  diversity 
it  shall  possess  for  us,  depends  upon  how  we  must  regulate 
our  conduct  to  obtain  the  satisfaction  of  our  will.  If  we 
must  act  as  if  there  were  other  individuals,  other  relatively 
independent  centers  of  activity,  then  there  are  other  indi- 
viduals ;  and  their  character  must  be  such  as  we  must  ad- 
just ourselves  to,  in  order  to  have  our  expectations  of  them 
realized,  in  order  to  live  properly.  If  we  regard  the  physical 
world  as  mechanical,  as  mere  means  to  an  end,  whereas  we 
recognize  human  beings  as  ends  in  themselves,  it  is  because 
only  by  distinguishing  such  objective  values  we  attain  the 
satisfaction,  or  good,  of  our  will.  Thus  both  the  diversity 
of  existence  and  the  diversity  of  meaning,  as  regards  the 
bigger  world,  are  known  through  the  differentiation  of  the 
activity  of  the  subject,  necessary  in  order  to  accomplish  its 
end. 

It  is  the  plurality  and  changeability  of  our  world  that  di- 
vorces truth  as  a  mental  structure  from  the  characters  of  the 
reality  it  means.  Our  meanings  must  readjust  themselves 
to  their  changing  objects  or  else  prove  false.  On  the  other 


The  Reality  of  Religious  Ideals  319 

hand,  truth  could  not  mean  reality,  could  be  nothing  but 
mere  shorthand,  unless  our  mental  structures  were  contin- 
uous with  their  environment.  Here  we  seem  to  have  an 
antinomy.  Both  discontinuity  and  continuity  seem  to  be 
necessary  in  order  to  account  for  the  nature  of  truth.  Mon- 
ism, by  affirming  the  unity  of  the  world  as  a  static  whole, 
has  failed  to  account  for  the  relativity  of  truth  as  it  attempts 
to  express  fact.  Pluralism  again,  of  the  old-fashioned  type, 
with  its  indifferent  substances,  made  unity  or  continuity  im- 
pojjsible,  and  hence  made  knowledge  impossible.  Both 
unity  and  plurality,  continuity  and  discontinuity,  must  be 
true  of  the  real,  though  under  different  conditions,  because 
we  must  act  as  if  they  were  true  in  order  properly  to  adjust 
ourselves  to  the  environment.  Both,  however,  must  be  rel- 
ative. The  concrete  truth  must  be  somehow  a  universe  of 
process  with  diversity  of  structure ;  with  relatively  stable 
centers  that  can  interact  and,  in  a  measure,  picture  each 
other ;  of  continuities  and  discontinuities  according  as  the 
conditions  are  present  or  absent  for  connecting  certain  en- 
ergies. If  we  must  adjust  ourselves  to  it  as  if  it  were  such, 
then  such  it  must  be,  even  though  we  may  not  now  be  able 
to  explain  how  it  is  so. 

II 

How  does  the  above  teleological  criterion  of  being  apply 
to  the  religious  environment  ?  We  have  seen  how  the  mind 
has  constructed  for  itself  and  projected  a  world  of  ideas  in 
order  to  meet  its  environment,  and  said,  "That  art  thou."  In 
so  far  as  its  prediction  has  been  verified  and  the  proper  ad- 
justment thus  obtained,  the  environment  has  replied,  "  That 
am  I."  The  character  we  have  given  this  environment 
has  depended  upon  the  needs  of  the  soul  to  make  itself 


32O  Truth  and  Reality 

at  home  in  the  world,  to  satisfy  its  wants.  The  environ- 
ment again  has  reacted  upon  the  adjustment  and  shown  how 
far  it  has  been  adequate.  Thus  we  have  come  to  construct 
an  inorganic,  an  organic  and  a  supra-organic  or  psychic 
environment,  each  of  which  grades  of  environment  has 
proven  its  reality  by  the  necessity  of  adjusting  ourselves  to 
it  in  order  for  the  highest  well-being.  But  in  this  historic 
process  of  adjustment  even  the  psychic  environment  of  so- 
cial unity  has  proven  inadequate  without  the  faith  in  an 
ultimate  spiritual  environment  which  shall  be  the  objectivity 
and  fulfillment  of  our  fragmentary  human  ideals.  Thus  the 
soul  of  man  has  built  itself  nobler  mansions,  has  constructed 
the  ideal  world  of  religion,  even  as  the  swallow  builds 
herself  a  nest  in  order  to  feel  cozier  and  more  at  home  in  an 
otherwise  cold  world.  Now,  does  the  religious  ideal  of  a 
realized  good  in  the  world  have  any  real  basis,  or  is  it  but 
a  fond  dream  ?  Is  there  any  environment  beyond  and  still 
higher  than  the  supra-organic  or  social  environment,  already 
so  difficult  for  us  to  grasp  and  yet  so  real  ?  Man  has  at  any 
rate  acted  upon  the  belief  in  such  an  unseen  environment, 
higher  than  the  human,  and  persists  in  doing  so.  Is  there 
any  justification  for  this? 

The  same  criterion  must  be  applied  to  the  reality  of  the 
religious  environment  as  has  been  applied  to  other  kinds  of 
environment.  I  can  see  no  intrinsic  difference  as  regards 
the  test  of  religious  concepts  or  hypotheses  from  the  test  of 
scientific.  The  former  are  more  momentous  hypotheses,  to 
be  sure,  but  that  does  not  alter  their  verification.  Science, 
too,  is  fundamentally  built  on  faith,  a  faith  built  on  very 
slender  evidence  —  the  faith  that  this  Chinese  puzzle  of  a 
world  can  be  sorted  and  be  made  to  fit  together  into  a  sys- 
tematic whole,  as  religion  is  built  upon  the  faith  in  a  Power 


The  Reality  of  Religious  Ideals  321 

that  is  righteous,  sympathizes  with,  and  works  for,  righteous- 
ness. In  any  case  the  idea  must  be  justified  or  proved  by  its 
consequences,  or  its  ability  to  satisfy  the  needs  of  the  individ- 
ual, or  at  any  rate  the  race  in  its  progressive  evolution.  As 
we  expect  the  scientific  demand  to  grow  more  definite  and 
articulate  in  the  course  of  evolution,  so  we  should  expect 
the  same  in  regard  to  the  religious  demands.  If  it  is  a  great 
distance  from  Thales  to  modern  science,  so  it  is  a  long  stretch 
from  the  Book  of  Judges  to  the  Sermon  on  the  Mount.  In 
the  case  of  science  and  religion  alike,  immediacy  —  whether 
the  immediacy  of  perception  as  in  science  or  the  vaguer 
immediacy  of  instinctive  feeling  as  in  religion  —  must  be 
interpreted  and  corrected  in  the  light  of  further  experi- 
ence. 

The  question  is :  Is  the  religious  environment  bound  up 
with  the  history  of  man  in  such  a  way  that  he  must  act  as 
if  it  were  real  in  order  to  attain  his  highest  development  ? 
If  the  religious  ideal  is  bound  up  with  moral  and  social  growth, 
as  well  as  the  highest  individual  appreciation  and  satisfac- 
tion ;  if  there  is  no  abatement  of  this  adjustment,  but,  on  the 
contrary,  if  it  increases  in  complexity  and  unity  with  the  de- 
velopment of  human  life ;  if  life  would  be  poorer  without 
it ;  if,  in  short,  the  religious  adjustment  has  proved  a  neces- 
sary one,  in  order  to  attain  the  highest  and  most  effective 
type ;  and  if  materialism  fails  to  inspire  such  a  type  of  life, 
then  the  religious  ideal  must  in  some  degree  possess  objec- 
tive reality.  Here,  too,  we  have  the  survival  of  the  fittest 
as  regards  beliefs ;  and  the  history  of  the  race  might  be 
written  as  the  history  of  religious  beliefs.  The  working  of 
the  religious  hypothesis  must  in  so  far  be  taken  as  evidence 
of  its  truthfulness,  just  as  the  working  of  the  scientific  hy- 
pothesis is  in  so  far  regarded  as  evidence  of  its  truth.  Both 


322  Truth  and  Reality 

must  be  modified  in  the  light  of  the  requirements  of  further 
experience.  The  progressive  usefulness  in  either  case  must 
prove  the  greater  objectivity  of  the  content.  Can  any  one 
doubt  the  cementing  influence  of  religious  beliefs  on  social 
unities,  or  the  heightening  effect  on  morality  of  the  faith  in 
an  impartial  and  sympathetic  Spectator  and  Cooperator,  or 
the  association  of  religion  with  the  highest  in  art  ?  And  as 
we  learn  to  substitute  more  and  more,  in  the  progress  of 
evolution,  inner  unity  for  mere  mechanical  coexistence,  are 
we  not  progressing  towards  the  appreciation  of  a  higher 
spiritual  supra-individual  unity  of  souls  greater  than  nations 
and  greater  than  humanity;  a  unity  which  is  not  a  mere 
block  unity,  like  that  of  Parmenides,  but  a  unity  which 
embodies  the  end  of  ideal  striving  ?  If  it  is  a  fact  that  the 
religious  ideal  is  thus  essential  to  the  highest  unity  and 
development  of  life,  then  the  religious  ideal  can  be  no  mere 
shadow  projected  by  the  imagination  of  man ;  but  it  becomes 
objective;  it  thickens  into  being.  It  is  the  ultimate  con- 
stitution of  the  cosmos. 

The  mistake  in  the  past  has  been  in  trying  to  express 
the  environment  of  the  individual  and  the  race  in  merely 
physical  or  perceptual  terms.  This  would  provide  no 
standard  of  fitness.  It  would  merely  record  the  fact  of 
survival,  and  stamp  that  fit  which  does  survive.  We  must, 
I  think,  regard  the  kingdom  not-of-this-world  as  no  less 
real  than  the  kingdom  of  this  world ;  the  realm  of  formal 
demands  and  ideals  no  less  real  than  the  realm  of  facts  and 
impulses.  And  not  only  must  the  former  be  as  real  as  the 
latter,  looked  at  from  the  point  of  view  of  existence,  but  the 
former  must  count  for  more,  must  legislate  to  the  latter ;  the 
ideal  environment  must  set  the  ultimate  survival  conditions 
of  the  natural.  Else  the  process  can  have  no  unity  or  mean- 


The  Reality  of  Religious  Ideals  323 

ing.  Else  no  generalization  would  be  possible.  Natural 
science  becomes  as  hopeless  as  ethics,  for  both  involve  the 
axiom  that  the  cosmic  process  has  direction,  or  is  amenable 
to  certain  ideals. 

What  has  been  said  with  reference  to  the  existence  of 
the  religious  environment  applies  equally  to  its  character. 
We  cannot  agree  with  Herbert  Spencer  that  utter  charac- 
terlessness, existence  without  content,  is  the  goal  of  religious 
progress.  What  possible  inspiration  could  mere  empty 
existence  have  in  human  evolution?  The  same  criterion 
which  shows  us  that  God  is,  shows  us  also  what  he  is. 
The  development  of  religion,  moreover,  shows  more  and 
more  agreement  as  regards  its  content.  All  the  developed 
religions  agree  in  maintaining,  though  with  different  em- 
phasis and  concreteness,  certain  attributes  as  indispensable. 
Thus  the  ideal  of  goodness,  as  the  supreme  factor  in  the 
religious  ideal,  is  common  to  all  the  great  religions.  It  is 
evident  that  the  more  empty  and  vague  the  religous  ideal 
is,  the  less  effective  it  is ;  and  that,  on  the  other  hand,  the 
religious  content  which  conduces  to  the  most  definite  under- 
standing of  man's  problems  and  contributes  most  to  the 
development  of  man  must  be  most  objective. 

We  can  only  mention  some  of  the  most  prominent  char- 
acters of  the  religious  ideal  which  have  proved  indispensable 
to  its  historic  efficiency.  One  is  the  unity  of  the  religious 
ideal  as  opposed  to  polytheism,  the  demand  for  one  unique 
and  final  embodiment  of  the  highest  good.  Furthermore, 
this  unity  must  be  a  personal  experience,  not  necessarily 
having  our  limitations,  but  capable  of  entering  into  sympa- 
thetic relations  with  all  good  strivings,  as  it  has  sufficient 
power  to  enforce  its  ideal.  God  must  not  be  merely  an 
impersonal  constitution.  Even  the  atheism  of  classical 


324  Truth  and  Reality 

Buddhism  could  not  be  made  practical  until  it  apotheosized 
the  founder. 

Practical  religion  must,  furthermore,  identify  itself  with 
the  values  or  norms  of  life  primarily.  In  other  words,  the 
religious  ideal  must  not  be  pantheistic.  Only  the  finite 
can  have  worth.  I  do  not  see  how  any  one  can  love  or 
worship  things  in  general,  this  medley  of  comedy  and 
tragedy,  of  harmony  and  discord,  which  we  call  a  world. 
Such  a  worship  would  seem  possible  only  by  killing  the 
nerve  of  activity,  by  saying  to  the  passing  moment, 
"Verweile  doch,  du  bist  so  schon,"  which,  if  we  believe 
Faust,  is  equivalent  to  selling  one's  self  to  the  devil. 
However  satisfying  such  a  view  may  be  esthetically,  it  is 
not  ethical.  Pantheism  is  as  unethical  as  materialism.  A 
God  that  is  identical  with  the  totality  of  existence  is  help- 
less to  redeem  the  world,  as  he  is  equally  responsible  for 
its  sins  and  its  virtues.  As  Plato  puts  it :  "  God,  if  he  be 
good,  is  not  the  author  of  all  things,  as  the  many  assert, 
but  he  is  the  cause  of  a  few  things  only,  and  not  of  most 
things  that  occur  to  men;  for  few  are  the  goods  of 
human  life,  and  many  are  the  evils,  and  the  good  only  is 
to  be  attributed  to  him :  of  the  evil  other  causes  have  to 
be  discovered." 1  Hence  Christianity  preaches  a  kingdom 
that  is  not  of  this  world,  a  God  of  righteousness.  "  Be 
ye  perfect  as  your  Father  in  Heaven  is  perfect."  God  is 
identified  with  the  absolute  worth  or  goodness  of  the 
world,  not  with  its  mere  brute  existence.  God  is  just,  as 
identified  with  the  realm  of  ideals,  and  as  such  he  sets 
survival  conditions  to  the  lower  finite  centers.  But  the  God 
required  by  human  experience  must  also  be  merciful,  and 
as  such,  he  strives  to  raise  our  finite  lives  to  the  standard. 
1  «  The  Republic,"  Bk.  II,  §  379. 


The  Reality  of  Religious  Ideals  325 

In  this  love  of  the  perfect  and  striving  to  make  the  finite 
perfect,  justice  is  not  abrogated  but  fulfilled.  The  world 
consists  of  many  centers  of  consciousness,  who  must  learn 
to  imitate,  and  make  their  own,  the  perfect  good,  each 
in  his  own  way.  And  in  this  lies  both  the  tragedy  and 
the  zest  of  life. 

The  truest  and  most  objective  religious  ideal,  then,  is 
that  which  can  furnish  the  completest  and  fullest  satisfac- 
tion of  the  demands  and  longings  of  evolving  humanity. 
The  various  religions,  no  matter  how  ancient  and  vener- 
able, must  submit  to  the  pragmatic  test,  their  ability  to 
minister  to  human  experience  in  all  its  complexity.  Relig- 
ions must  not  appeal  merely  to  our  credulity  for  the  mirac- 
ulous. In  that  case  the  savage  religions  would  rank  at 
the  top ;  for,  in  the  absence  of  science,  there  is  no  limit  to 
the  miraculous.  Nor  must  the  appeal  be  to  a  mere  super- 
natural revelation  or  authority.  In  that  case  Brahmanism 
and  the  old  Pharisaism  would  rank  foremost.  Religions 
must  appeal  to  the  good  sense  of  man ;  they  must  increase 
his  perspective  or  sanity.  They  must  enable  him  to  think 
more  deeply  and  truly ;  to  appreciate  and  create  greater 
beauty;  to  live  more  completely  and  fully,  individually 
and  socially.  Christianity  neither  can  nor  must  claim  any 
exemption  from  this  test  of  the  completest  ministry  to 
human  nature.  With  this  it  stands  or  falls,  not  with  its 
ecclesiasticism  or  creeds.  For  the  Sabbath  was  made  for 
man,  and  not  man  for  the  Sabbath. 

Christianity  is  the  highest  religion  to  us  because  it,  as 
no  other,  furnishes,  in  the  simplest  and  completest  way, 
that  environment  of  the  soul  which  satisfies  and  makes 
objective  its  yearning  for  the  highest  good.  And  inasmuch 
as  the  personality  of  Jesus  answers  all  our  demands  for 


326  Truth  and  Reality 

personal  goodness,  as  no  other  historic  individual  does  — 
fulfills  them  not  only  relatively  but  completely  —  we  must 
acknowledge  him  as  divine  in  a  unique  way.  He  is  to  the 
Western  world,  at  any  rate,  the  concrete  universal,  the 
beautiful  life  —  not  only  individually  beautiful  and  com- 
plete, as  a  work  of  art,  but  the  greatest  energizing  power 
for  beauty,  truth  and  goodness.  Nor  is  his  claim  to  this 
position  waning,  but  ever  gaining  new  strength  in  the  dis- 
solution of  dogmas  and  the  crash  of  creeds.  And  in  the 
struggle  for  survival  which  is  now  going  on  between  the 
Western  and  Eastern  world,  in  spite  of,  yea  from,  the  smoke 
and  din  of  battle  and  secular  conquest,  the  ideal  dominion 
of  the  Galilean  promises  to  extend  itself,  in  the  centuries 
to  come,  to  the  ends  of  the  earth. 


INDEX 


Absolute  experience,  the  hypothesis  of 
the  universe  as  an,  109-111,  160-161. 

Absolute  idealism,  insistence  on  internal 
relations  of  consciousness  by,  109. 

Absolute  truth,  the  attainability  of,  115- 
122. 

Abstractive  method  in  metaphysics, 
297  ff. 

Adjustments,  life  and  knowledge  viewed 
as,  308-315. 

Adolescence,  reason  for  the  period  of,  18. 

Affirmative  judgment,  priority  of  nega- 
tive judgment  to,  87-90. 

Agnosticism,  lack  of  sympathy  of  meta- 
physics for,  294-295. 

Agreement,  validity  stated  as  the,  of  an 
idea  or  belief  with  its  reality,  210-211 ; 
discussion  of  the  nature  of,  214  ff. 

Analogy,  proper  use  of,  in  framing  hy- 
potheses, 131-132,  133. 

Anaxogoras,  mentioned,  214. 

Animals,  development  of  brain  of,  con- 
trasted with  development  of  human 
beings,  17-18;  difference  in  growth 
span  of  man  and  of,  18;  response  to 
stimuli  of  children  and  of  young,  21- 
22 ;  erperiments  with,  to  show  inter- 
dependence of  associative  memory  and 
social  instincts,  27-28;  habit  among, 
47 ;  importance  of  imitation  among, 
48 ;  conception  of  ideal  wholes  absent 
in,  57;  relations  of  thought  and 
language  illustrated  by,  73. 
Aristotle,  103 ;  quoted  regarding  law  of 
nnitude,  142 ;  quoted  on  metaphysics, 
300. 

Art,  the  elasticity  of,  7-8;  claim  of 
esthetic  objects  to  title  of,  72;  dis- 
tinction between  science  and,  289-290. 
Association,  connection  between  language 
and  the  laws  of,  74;  the  operation  ol 
thought  through,  84-85. 


Associative  memory,  a  stage  in  develop- 
ment of  consciousness,  17 ;  instincts 
characteristicjof  the  stage  of,  25  ff. ; 
appearance  of  the  social  instincts 
together  with,  27 ;  cumulative  mean- 
ing on  the  level  of,  67. 

Augustine,  10,  215. 

Baldwin,  James  Mark,  42  n. ;  definition 
of  ideal  synthesis  by,  55. 

Belief  and  validity,  102-103,  200.  210- 
211. 

Bergson,  Henry,  75,  222. 

Berkeley,  257,  296. 

Biological  heritage,  limitations  in  truth 
seeking  due  to  our,  240. 

Bradley,  144,  217,  279,  285. 

Brain  of  animals  and  of  man,  develop- 
ment of,  17-18. 

Burnet,  "Early  Greek  Philosophers"  by, 
cited,  1 66,  170. 

Butler,  309. 

Caird,  John,  257. 

Cams,  Paul,  43  n. ;  quoted  on  pragma- 
tism, 178. 

Categories  of  intelligence,  the,  43  ff. 

Cause  and  effect,  the  synthesis  of, 
among  categories  on  level  of  generali- 
zation, 53-54. 

Chicken,  reactions  of,  to  stimuli,  com- 
pared with  those  of  the  human  child, 
21-22. 

Chinese,  illustration  drawn  from  re- 
ligions of  the,  5-6. 

Christianity,  the  highest  religion,  324- 
326. 

Cognitive  meaning,  realism  concerns  the 
relation  of  the,  to  its  object,  252. 

Cognitive  relations  contributed  by  human 
nature  to  nature,  232-234. 

Cold-storage  judgment,  the  so-called,  95- 
96. 


327 


328 


Index 


Compounding,  the  activity  of,  among 
operations  of  the  mind,  104  ff. 

Concept,  place  of  the,  in  the  thought  pro- 
cess, 04-95 ;  necessity  of  the,  230-240. 

Concepts,  crystallization  of,  into  objec- 
tive facts,  308  ff . ;  not  to  be  held  as 
merely  convenient  symbols,  317-318. 

Conceptual  construction  vs.  perceptual 
qualities,  262-268. 

Conduct,  termination  of  thinking  in  types 
of,  78;  different  stages  of,  78-79;  the 
function  of  truth  is  to  regulate,  123- 
124;  significance  of  the  term,  183-184. 

Conscience,  evaluation  of  life  by,  159. 

Consciousness,  initial  stages  of,  15-17; 
part  of  spectator  taken  by,  in  physio- 
logical stage  of  mind-development,  20- 
24 ;  in  the  stage  of  associative  memory, 
25-28;  in  the  stage  of  reflective  mean- 
ing, 28-34;  psychological  analysis  of 
the  relational,  107-108;  epistemo- 
logical  significance  of  relational  con- 
tent of,  108  ff. ;  as  awareness,  268, 
304-305. 

Consistency,  the  law  of,  126-133,  146; 
tests  of  the  law,  148-154. 

Content  of  truth,  the,  104  ff. 

Contexts,  objective,  269-276;  relation 
of,  to  each  other,  276-280. 

Contiguity,  the  law  of,  among  categories 
of  reproductive  imagination,  49. 

Contradiction,  the  law  of,  126  ff. 

Conventionality  of  truth,  question  of, 
285-288. 

Coordinations,  spatial,  recognition  of  on 
perceptual  level  of  intelligence,  44-45. 

Copying  theory  of  knowledge,  221-222. 

Correspondence,  of  truth  and  reality, 
214  ff. ;  the  real  meaning  of,  216-217; 
the  instrumental  and  the  sharing  sig- 
nificance of,  217-219. 

Cosmic  selection,  individual  and  social 
selection  subject  to,  212-213. 

Criterion  of  truth,  the,  165  ff. 

Critical  method,  substitution  of,  for  dog- 
matic, in  philosophic  thought,  260  ff. 

"  Critique  of  Pure  Reason,"  Kant's,  43. 

Curiosity  a  motive  in  truth-seeking,  235. 

Darwinian  theory,  294,  299. 
Deduction,  analysis  of,  99-100. 
Democritus,  10-11,  124. 
Descartes,  215. 


Dewey,  "Logical  Studies,"  181  n. 
Discrimination,  begins  on  the  prelogical 

level,  68. 

Docility,  the  attitude  called,  33. 
Dogmatic  fallacies  of  the  past,  254-259. 
Dualistic  type  of  realism,  the,  222-223. 
Duality,  law  of,  138-141,  147. 
Duration,  the  sense  of,  on  the  perceptual 

level,  45-46.    See  Time. 

Education,  experiments  in,  4 ;  possibility 
of,  determined  by  our  evolutionary 
heritage,  15.  <£  2, 

Ego,  accounting  for  the,  310  ff. 

Egoistic-preservative  instincts,  appear- 
ance of,  20-24. 

Eleatics,  Protagoras  and  the,  169-175. 

Elimination,  process  of,  exercised  by  in- 
stinct mechanism  in  physiological  stage, 
24. 

Eliot,  President,  quoted  on  experiments 
in  education,  4. 

Empedocles,  quoted,  170,  214. 

Empiricism,  pragmatism  and,  197-198; 
discussion  of,  262-264;  emphasis 
placed  by  on  man's  adjustments  at 
expense  of  the  individual,  309-310. 

Energy,  metaphysics  and  the  concept  of, 
299;  classification  of  energies,  303. 

Environment,  office  of,  to  furnish  stimuli, 
15,  17.  37-40;  the  individual's  debt  to 
his,  309-316;  consideration  of  man's 
religious,  321-323. 

Epistemological  significance  of  the  rela- 
tional consciousness,  108-111. 

Estheticism,  6-8,  71-72,  159. 

Esthetic  unity,  characteristics  of,  71 ;  to 
be  distinguished  from  thought  unity, 
71-72. 

Etemalism,  pragmatism  and,  198. 

Evolution,  240;  theory  of,  and  meta- 
physics, 299. 

Existence,  problems  of,  with  which  meta- 
physics deals,  302-304. 

Expectancy,  a  stage  in  development  of 
consciousness,  17. 

Experience,  an  ideal  unity  of,  63-64; 
the  proposition  that  only  experience 
can  make  a  difference  to,  254-256. 

Faith,  relation  of  thought  to,  156-157; 
the  element  of,  hi  philosophical  and  in 
scientific  hypotheses,  3 17-318, 320-321. 


Index 


329 


Fallacies,  certain  fundamental,  of  philo- 
sophic thought,  254-259. 

Family,  a  necessary  institution  for  man 
on  account  of  length  of  growth  span, 
18. 

Fashions  in  thinking,  force  of,  and  limi- 
tations resulting  from,  68-69,  245-246, 

273- 

Fichte,  the  philosophy  of,  12-13,  231-232. 
Finitude,  the  law  of,  141-145,  147-148; 

tests  of  the  law,  148-154. 
Flechsig,  31. 
Foetus,  response  of,  to  stimuli,  resulting 

in  a  structural  series,  16. 

Generalization,  the  level  of,  among  cate- 
gories of  intelligence,  51-55. 

God,  the  concept  of,  64;  use  of,  as  a 
perceptive  factor,  by  certain  philos- 
ophers, 231-232;  philosophic  attain- 
ment to  concept  and  character  of,  323- 
326. 

Gomperz,  "Greek  Thinkers,"  cited,  165, 
169- 

Goodness,  the  ideal  of,  common  to  the 
great  religions,  323. 

Green,  mentioned,  257. 

Habit,  instincts  on  the  sensitive  level 
made  definite  by,  24;  considered  as 
a  fundamental  category  on  the  per- 
ceptual level,  47. 

Hegel,  10,  150-160,  257;  introspective 
account  of  thought  by,  77-78;  recog- 
nition by,  of  the  negativitat  in  system- 
atic thought,  90. 

Hegelian  absolute,  the,  31. 

Heraclitus,  166. 

Hilbert,  D.,  quoted,  142. 

Homo  mensura  doctrine  of  Protagoras, 
4,  170,  171. 

Humanism,  pragmatism  not  equivalent 
to,  191-193 ;  the  meaning  of,  230-234. 

Human  nature,  the  definition  of,  168- 
172 ;  and  truth,  230-247 ;  limitations 
of,  in  search  for  knowledge,  239-247. 

Hume,  David,  119,  215,  233,  310,  311. 

Huxley,  T.  H.,  293. 

Hypotheses,  the  importance  of,  as  shown 
by  modern  science,  175-176;  testing 
of,  by  the  method  of  pragmatism,  186  ff . 

Hypothetical  stage  in  the  development  of 
the  judging  process,  93. 


Idealism,  5 ;  insistence  on  internal  rela- 
tions by  absolute,  109 ;  effort  made  by, 
to  give  a  systematic  account  of  ex- 
perience, 1 60;  discussion  of  pragmatic 
realism  as  placed  over  against,  251  ff. ; 
merit  of,  in  interpretation  of  institu- 
tional life,  256-257;  weakness  of,  in 
dealing  with  nature,  257. 

Idealization,  the  level  of,  among  cate- 
gories of  intelligence,  55-64. 

Ideal  synthesis,  definition  of,  55-58 ;  dis- 
tinction between  thought  and,  71-72. 

Ideal  unity,  forms  of,  57-64. 

Identification,  the  real  meaning  of 
thought,  98;  quality  of  truth  as, 
rather  than  falsification,  300-301. 

Identities,  physical  and  social,  269-276. 

Identity,  the  law  of,  126  ff. ;  insistence 
on  identity  of  stuff  by  dogmatism, 
254-256. 

Imageless  thought,  79-80. 

Imagery  of  the  thought  process,  200  ff . 

Imagination,  the  level  of  reproductive, 
48-51. 

Imitation,  reaction  on  behavior  stimuli 
called,  23 ;  does  not  create  tendencies, 
31 ;  a  fundamental  category  on  the 
perceptual  level,  48;  as  shown  in 
thought-fashions,  68-69. 

Immediacy,  in  the  philosophy  of  Pro- 
tagoras, 168-175 ;  the  importance  of,  as 
shown  by  modern  science,  175-180; 
of  perception,  interpretation  and  cor- 
rection of,  in  light  of  further  experi- 
ence, 321. 

Implicit  and  explicit,  idealistic  play  upon 
the,  258-259. 

Individual,  definition  of  the,  310  ff. 

Individual  contexts,  275-276;  relations 
of,  to  social  and  physical  contexts, 
277-279. 

Individual  interpenetration,  synthesis  of, 
among  categories  on  the  level  of 
generalization,  54-55. 

Individualism,  in  the  philosophy  of  Pro- 
tagoras, 168-175. 

Individual  judgment,  social  agreement  vs., 
211-212. 

Induction,  analysis  of,  99-100. 

Inference,  expansion  of  the  judgment 
into  its  reasons,  08. 

Infinite,  not  to  be  regarded  as  of  the 
nature  of  thought,  141-145. 


330 


Index 


Instinct,  mind  as,  15  6. ;  defined  as  a 
response  to  stimulus  determined  by 
congenital  structure,  18;  stages  of,  20; 
reason  and,  contrasted,  83;  relations 
of  intelligence  and,  120. 

Instinctive  heritage,  limitations  in  truth- 
seeking  resulting  from  our,  244-245. 

Instincts,  on  the  sensitive  stage,  20-24; 
the  egoistic-preservative,  on  the  sensi- 
tive stage  of  development,  20-24 ;  con- 
trast of  those  of  children  and  of  young 
animals,  21-22 ;  the  action  of,  regarded 
as  a  penny-in-the-slot  affair,  22;  the 
stage  of  associative  memory,  25  fif. ; 
appearance  of  reflection  and  the  third 
stage  of,  26  ff. ;  appearance  of  the 
social,  27-28;  the  ideal,  which  appear 
with  stage  of  reflective  meaning,  28-34. 

Institutional  life,  40 ;  idealism  strong  in 
interpretation  of,  256-257. 

Instrumental  relation  of  knowledge,  217- 
219,  227-228. 

Intelligence,  defined  as  capacity  to  learn 
from  experience,  43 ;  the  categories  of, 
43  ff. ;  conative  character  of,  43-44; 
the  perceptual  level  of,  44  ff. ;  rela- 
tions of  instinct  and,  120. 

Interaction,  the  problem  of,  303-304. 

Interest,  the  element  of,  in  truth-seeking, 
235;  nature  of,  influenced  by  racial 
and  individual  differences,  241-243. 

James,  William,  the  philosophy  of,  12- 
13,  31 1  Protagoras  and,  165 ;  teleo- 
logical  nature  of  the  thought  process 
shown  by,  181;  mentioned,  190,  260; 
on  the  "mystical  illumination"  test  of 
truth,  207 ;  new  theory  of  knowledge 
developed  by,  215-216;  division  by, 
of  human  beings  into  tough-minded 
and  tender-minded,  242. 

Jesus,  divinity  of,  325-326. 

Joachim,  "The  Nature  of  Truth,"  quoted, 
no. 

Judgment,  definition  of,  86;  a  back- 
ground of  habit  and  imitation  for,  87 ; 
priority  of  negative  over  affirmative, 
87-90;  psychological  priority  to  be 
distinguished  from  its  logical  signifi- 
cance, 90;  hypothetical  stage  in 
development  of,  93 ;  the  categorical 
stage,  94,  95-97;  the  "cold-storage" 
judgment,  06;  relations  of  content  of 


truth  and,  106  ff. ;  the  subject-object 
relation  presupposed  by,  139  ff. 

Kallen,  H.  M.,  185  n. 

Kant,  Immanuel,  the  philosophy  of,  12- 
13,  30,  43,  52,  S3,  54,  56-57,  59  ff-, 
208,  209,  215,  217,  218,  231,  310-311. 

Keller,  Helen,  264-265. 

Knowledge,  Locke's  scheme  of,  104-106 ; 
views  of,  of  absolute  idealists,  109-111 ; 
the  law  of  finitude  applied  to,  141-145 ; 
the  problem  of,  according  to  Protag- 
oras and  Plato,  168-175;  means  the 
differences  that  stimuli  make  to  reflect- 
ive human  nature,  183 ;  new  theory 
of,  developed  by  modern  philosophers, 
215-216;  the  instrumental  relation  of, 
217-219;  the  sharing  relation  of,  217, 
219-222;  overlapping  problems  of, 
260  ff.,  301-302;  inter-dependence  of 
theory  of,  and  theory  of  reality,  301. 

Language,  reasoning  not  necessary  to 
existence  of,  29;  relation  existing 
between  thought  and,  72-76,  79,  80; 
effect  of  close  association  of  our  ex- 
perience and,  273. 

Laws  of  thought,  investigation  of  the, 
124-126.  See  postulates. 

Leibniz,  119,  134,  221,  253. 

Life,  various  methods  of  evaluating,  150- 
160;  certain  philosophic  definitions  of, 
308-309. 

Like,  the  axiom  that  only  like  can  act 
upon,  254-256. 

Limitations  of  human  nature  in  its  search 
for  knowledge,  239-247. 

Locke,  "  Essay  concerning  Human  Under- 
standing," quoted,  104,  105,  106,  107. 

Lotze,  "Logic,"  cited,  153. 

Lovejoy,  the  "Thirteen  Pragmatisms" 
of,  190  n. 

Mathematical  models,  confusion  of  truth 
and,  208-209. 

Meaning,  distinction  between  thought 
and  the  prelogical  stages  of,  67-68; 
and  validity,  200  ff . ;  the  concept  of, 
200-201 ;  truth  not  a  coincident  term 
with,  201 ;  ultimate  validity  of,  deter- 
mined by  cosmic  selection,  212-213. 

Melissos,  quoted,  169. 

Metaphysics,  to  be  considered  a  science, 


Index 


331 


rather  than  an  art,  288-290;  what  is 
meant  by,  290-293 ;  provisional  and 
conflicting  sciences  opposed  to,  293- 
296 ;  criticism  and  clarification  of  over- 
lapping problems  by,  296-297;  and 
the  concept  of  energy,  299 ;  and  evolu- 
tionary theory,  209;  larger  correla- 
tion of  sequences  and  values  of  the 
special  sciences  aimed  at  by,  209-300. 

Mind  as  instinct,  15  ff. 

More,  Louis  T.,  articles  by,  291  n. ; 
quoted,  292. 

Morgan,  C.  Lloyd,  17,  22,  25,  42  n.; 
quoted,  45. 

Morphology  of  truth,  the,  86  ff. 

Motive,  relation  of,  to  validity  in  truth- 
seeking,  234-239. 

Munsterberg,  Hugo,  31,  300. 

Mystical  illumination  of  certain  moments 
as  a  test  of  truth,  207-208. 

Natural  selection,  progress  through  spon- 
taneous variations  and,  15;  hierarchy 
of  instincts  provided  for  by,  17-18; 
group  supplementation  of  instincts  by, 
25 ;  stages  of  instinct  mechanism  tele- 
scoped into  one  another  by,  25,  34. 

Nature,  the  contribution  of  human  nature 
to,  231-234 ;  context  of,  275-276. 

No  consciousness,  the,  91-92. 

Nominalism,  confusion  of  thought  with 
language  by,  75;  taken  in  the  bald 
sense  of  absolute  disparateness,  would 
make  truth  impossible,  127-128;  rela- 
tion of  pragmatism  to,  184-185. 

Number,  the  ideal  universe  of,  111-112. 

Object  and  its  contexts,  the,  269  ff. 

Occam,  mentioned,  215. 

Ontological  absolute,  the,  109-110,  160. 

Optimism,  world  philosophy  of,  w.  that 
of  pessimism,  243. 

Overlapping  problems,  274;  metaphysics 
and  the,  296  ff . ;  fundamental  types  of, 
for  philosophy  to  deal  with,  301-306. 

Pantheism,  323,  324. 

Part-relations  of  content  of  truth,  ni- 

114. 
Peirce,  C.  S.,  use  of  term  pragmatism  by, 

184,  260. 
Perceptual  level  of  intelligence,  44-48; 

cumulative  meaning  on  the,  67. 
Perceptual  qualities,  262-266. 


Philosophy,  a  plea  for  tolerance  in,  3-14. 

Physical  contexts,  269-270,  274-276; 
relation  of,  to  social  and  individual 
contexts,  276-277. 

Pillsbury,  "The  Psychology  of  Reason- 
ing" by,  102  n. 

Plato,  quoted,  4;  variation  in  the 
philosophy  of,  6-7 ;  the  philosophy  of, 
10,  142;  on  the  impossibility  of  a 
logical  definition  of  knowledge,  153- 
154;  the  "Theatetus"  of,  160-175; 
interpretation  of  human  nature  of,  171 ; 
quoted  on  satisfaction  as  a  criterion 
in  truth-seeking,  238 ;  quoted  on  con- 
ception of  God,  324. 

Pleasure  and  pain  values  as  guides  in 
the  working  of  instincts,  22-23. 

Poetry,  consistency  not  demanded  in, 
7-8. 

Postulates  of  truth,  the,  123  ff. ;  proofs 
of  the,  148-154. 

Pragmatic  method,  applied  to  the  tak- 
ing of  experience,  58;  applied  to  the 
ideal  synthesis  of  outer  experience  or 
nature,  60. 

Pragmatism,  a  theory  of  the  function  of 
truth,  1 23 ;  historic  orientation  of, 
165  ff . ;  agreement  of  Protagoras  and 
modern,  165-168;  defined  as  scientific 
method  conscious  of  its  own  procedure, 
177;  modern  and  ancient,  compared, 
180-183 ;  significance  of  the  term  con- 
duct, 183-184;  relation  of  pragmatism 
to  nominalism,  184-185;  discussion  of 
what  pragmatism  is  and  is  not,  186- 
199;  signifies  the  carrying  of  the 
scientific  spirit  into  metaphysics,  260 

Pragmatic  realism,  definition  and  dis- 
cussion of,  251-268. 

Prestige,  effects  of,  in  thinking,  68-09, 
245,  273- 

Priestley,  10-11. 

Processes,  the  problem  of  diverse,  302- 

303- 
Protagoras,  the  empiricism  of,  165  ff. ; 

value  of  work  of,  against  the  a  priorizm 

of  the  Eleatics,  160-175. 
Psychological  analysis,  of  thought,  76- 

81;    of  the  relational   consciousness, 

107-108. 

Qualities,  perceptual,  and  those  existing 
independent  of  perception,  262-268. 


332 


Index 


Quality,  the  synthesis  of,  among  cate- 
gories on  level  of  generalization,  52-53. 
Quantity,  the  synthesis  of,  51-52. 

Race,  fundamental  differences  in  genius 
due  to  differences  in,  241-242. 

Realism,  and  the  content  of  truth,  113- 
115;  pragmatism  and,  194;  discus- 
sion of  the  definition  of,  251-254; 
discussion  and  clearing  away  of  objec- 
tions against,  254-259;  consequences 
resulting  from  pragmatic  realism,  260- 
248. 

Reality,  the  agreement  of  truth  and,  dis- 
cussed, 214-229;  stuff  and  non-stuff 
character  of,  267-268;  interdepend- 
ence of  theory  of,  and  theory  of 
knowledge,  301 ;  problems  concerning 
fundamental  concepts  of,  301-305. 

Reason,  instinct  and,  contrasted,  83. 

Reasoning,  and  language,  29. 

Recapitulation,  explanation  of  instincts 
as,  24. 

Reciprocity,  not  a  distinct  category  on 
the  level  of  generalization,  54. 

Reference  or  duality,  the  law  of,  138- 
141,  147. 

Reflection,  a  stage  in  development  of 
consciousness,  17;  development  of 
power  of,  in  third  stage  of  instinct,  26  ff . 

Relating,  the  process  of,  as  concerned 
with  the  truth  process,  104  ft. 

Relations,  internal  and  external,  and  the 
process  of  truth,  104-121 ;  Locke's 
scheme  of  knowledge  on  the  basis  of, 
105. 

Relativity  of  values,  the  doctrine  of,  166- 
167. 

Religion,  determined  by  our  instinctive 
tendencies,  40-41. 

Religious  experience,  the  content  of,  115. 

Religious  ideals,  the  reality  of,  307-326. 

Reproductive  imagination,  the  level  of, 
48-51;  three  categories  of:  conti- 
guity, similarity,  and  set,  49. 

Royce,  Josiah,  the  philosophy  of,  10,  31, 
160,  257;  "The  Conception  of  God" 
by,  quoted,  109-110. 
Russell,  "Philosophical  Essays,"  quoted, 
107, 108 ;  "  Foundations  of  Geometry  " 
by,  quoted,  141. 

Satisfaction  as  a  criterion  in  truth- 
seeking,  193-194,  204-205,  237-239. 


Schiller,  F.  C.  S.,  181  n.,  230  n. 

Science,  metaphysics  as  a,  288-290;  ap- 
plication of,  to  study  of  religion,  307. 

Sciences,  bearing  of  metaphysics  on  the 
special,  297-301. 

Seeming,  Protagoras'  and  Plato's  defi- 
nition of,  171-175. 

Sensations  and  reality,  264-265. 

Sensitiveness,  considered  as  a  stage  of 
consciousness,  17. 

Separating,  the  activity  of,  among  opera- 
tions of  the  mind,  104  ff. 

Set,  a  category  of  reproductive  imagina- 
tion, 50-51 ;  the  thought  set  a  unique 
fact,  not  reducible  to  sensations,  108. 

Sharing  relation  of  knowledge,  217,  219- 

222. 

Similarity,  a  category  of  reproductive 
imagination,  49-50. 

Social  agreement  not  the  final  test  of 
truth,  211-212,  270-272. 

Social  contexts,  270-275. 

Social  instincts,  evolution  of  the,  27 ; 
interdependence  of  associative  memory 
and,  27-28. 

Socrates,  significance  of  the  concept  to, 
95;  on  relativity  of  values,  167. 

Space,  the  problem  of,  304. 

Space  coordinations,  on  perceptual  level 
of  intelligence,  44-45. 

Spencer,  Herbert,  39,  209,  210;  sugges- 
tive definition  of  life  by,  308. 

Spinoza,  135-136. 

Stimuli,  structural  tendencies  of  the 
organic  growth  series  called  into  play 
by,  15;  response  of  the  foetus  to,  16; 
development  of  the  organism  in 
obedience  to,  16-17 ;  responses  to, 
which  constitute  instinct,  20-24;  ap- 
pearance of  reason  in  response  to,  30- 
31 ;  responses  to,  at  various  levels  of 
intellectual  development,  43-64. 

Stout,  Professor,  43-44. 

Stuff,  fallacious  assumption  that  all  that 
is  not,  cannot  be  real,  259;  the  world 
of,  and  the  world  of  non-stuff,  267-268 ; 
the  problem  concerning,  302-303. 

Subject-object  relation  presupposed  by 
truth,  138-141,  147 ;  tests  of  the  law, 
148-154. 

Survival  conditions,  changes  in,  in 
civilized  environments,  38-39. 

Syllogism,  the,  as  a  linguistic  device,  79, 


Index 


333 


100-102 ;  value  of  the,  for  abstracting 
and  investigating  valid  thought  rela- 
tions, 125. 

Teleological  criterion  of  being,  applied  to 
the  religious  environment,  319-320. 

Teleological  relation  of  whole  and  part, 
111-114,  117,  119,  193. 

Temperament,  limitations  in  search  for 
knowledge  resulting  from  differences 
in,  242-244. 

Tendencies,  survival  value  of,  variation 
in,  and  effect  of,  37-42. 

Thought,  to  be  distinguished  from  pre- 
logical  stages  of  meaning,  67-68; 
fashions  in,  68-69,  273;  not  neces- 
sarily involved  in  adaptation  of  means 
to  ends,  69-70;  a  form  of  volitional 
conduct,  70 ;  debt  of,  to  more  concrete 
forms  of  unity,  such  as  complication 
and  association,  70-71;  to  be  distin- 
guished from  other  forms  of  ideal  syn- 
thesis, such  as  esthetic  unity,  71-72; 
relation  existing  between  language  and, 
72-76,  79,  80,  273;  psychological  in- 
vestigations of,  76-81 ;  question  of 
imageless,  79-80 ;  a  volitional  process, 
81-82 ;  definition  and  discussion  of  the 
thought  attitude  proper,  81-85;  the 
act  of  judgment  the  real  core  of  thought 
activity,  86 ;  implies  a  problem  and  its 
solution,  86-87 ;  priority  of  negative 
judgment  over  the  affirmative,  87-90; 
place  of  the  no  consciousness,  91-92; 
the  real  meaning  of,  is  identification, 
98,  300;  induction  and  deduction, 
99-100 ;  psychological  analysis  of  the 
relational  consciousness,  107-108  ; 
truth  created  rather  than  found  by, 
121 ;  the  question  of  the  nature  of, 
123-126;  the  law  of  finitude,  141-145; 
relation  of  the  will  to,  154  ff. ;  not  to  be 
held  the  only  way  of  evaluating  life,  159. 

Thought  process,  the,  67  ff. 

Time,  sense  of  duration  of,  on  perceptual 
level  of  intelligence,  45-46 ;  the  factor 
of,  among  limitations  of  human  nature 
in  its  search  for  knowledge,  246-247, 
268,  280-285;  dealt  with  as  an  over- 
lapping problem,  304. 

Tolerance,  a  plea  for  philosophic,  3-14. 

Totality,  the  law  of,  133-138,  146 ;  tests 
of  the  law,  148-154. 


Trial,  instincts  on  the  sensitive  level 
made  definite  by,  24. 

Truth,  the  morphology  of,  86  ff. ;  grounds 
of,  confused  with  grounds  of  belief, 
102-103 ;  the  content  of,  104  ff . ;  the 
process  of  relating  and  the  process  of, 
104-122;  the  question  of  the  attain- 
ability of  absolute,  115-122;  question 
whether  thought  finds  or  creates,  121 ; 
the  postulates  of,  1 23  ff . ;  the  function 
of,  to  regulate  conduct,  123-124;  the 
law  of  consistency,  including  the  laws 
of  identity  and  of  contradiction,  126- 
133;  the  law  of  totality,  133-138;  the 
law  that  truth  must  be  representative, 
or  that  it  presupposes  the  subject- 
object  relation,  138-141 ;  the  law  of 
finitude,  141-145;  proofs  of  the  pos- 
tulates of,  148-154;  to  be  considered 
an  adjective  of  thinking,  an  active 
sorting  of  reality  as  experienced,  158; 
the  criterion  of,  165  ff. ;  Plato's  defi- 
nition of,  173;  the  author's  tentative 
definition  of,  183;  pragmatism  as  a 
practical  theory  of,  183-184 ;  question 
of  the  usefulness  of,  191 ;  guesses  and, 
195-196;  is  systematic  meaning,  cor- 
rected and  completed  in  its  intended 
reality,  195-196 ;  the  test  of,  196-197 ; 
and  usefulness,  203 ;  not  to  be  defined 
in  terms  of  satisfaction,  204-206 ;  the 
"mystical  illumination"  test  of,  207- 
208;  mathematical  and  moral  prop- 
ositions and,  208;  intuitional  or 
categorical  certainty  test,  208-209; 
"impossibility  of  the  contrary"  test, 
209-210;  consists  in  the  agreement 
of  an  idea  or  belief  with  its  reality, 
210—211;  social  agreement  not  a 
final  test  of,  as  opposed  to  individual 
judgment,  211-212;  must  agree  with 
the  future,  212;  cosmic  selection  and 
its  effects  on,  212-213 ;  and  agreement, 
214  ff. ;  human  nature  and,  230  ff. ; 
relation  of  motive  to  validity  in  seek- 
ing, 234-239;  the  element  of  interest 
in  seeking,  235 ;  what  constitutes  the 
validity  of,  236;  the  element  of  time 
in  the  search  for,  268,  280-285 .'  ques- 
tion of  conventional  character  of,  285- 
288 ;  and  metaphysics,  288-200,  291  ff . ; 
the  overlapping  problems,  301-305; 
and  religious  ideals,  307-326. 


334 


Index 


Truth  process,  the,  67  ff. ;  is  self-realiza- 
tion, the  will  to  know,  85 ;  the  various 
stages  of  the,  86  ff. 

Unity  of  experience,  an  ideal,  63-64. 

Unity  of  history,  the  demand  for  an  ideal, 
62-63. 

Unity  of  nature,  realization  of  the,  61,  63. 

Unity  of  religious  ideal,  323-324. 

Unity  of  the  self,  the  demand  for  the, 
57~58;  a  goal  to  be  accomplished, 
rather  than  a  finished  fact,  59-60. 

Universal  invariant,  the,  286-287. 

Universe,  hypothesis  of  the,  as  an  abso- 
lute experience,  loo-iu,  160-161. 

Usefulness  of  truth,  question  of  the,  191, 
203. 

Validity,  basis  of,  confused  with  basis 
of  belief,  102-103 ;  meaning  and, 
200  ff . ;  stated  as  the  agreement  of  an 
idea  or  belief  with  its  reality,  210-211 ; 
relation  of  motive  to,  in  truth-seeking, 
234-239 ;  of  our  religious  ideals,  307  ff . 


Value,  the  problem  of,  305. 

Values,  Protagoras'  doctrine  of  the  rela- 
tivity of,  166-167. 

Variations,  theory  that  progress  takes 
place  through  spontaneous,  and  natural 
selection,  15;  operation  of  the  sur- 
vival variations  longitudinally  as  well 
as  sectionally  in  development,  19;  ex- 
planation of  variations  in  tastes  and 
tendencies  of  different  persons  and 
classes,  31-33. 

Whole  and  part,  teleological  relation  of, 

111-114,  H9>  193- 
Will,  relation  of  the,  to  thought,  154  ff. 

Xenophanes,  on  guesses  and  truth, 
195- 

Zeno,  philosophy  of,  169,  209. 

Zero,    fallacious   assumptions   regarding 

unthinkableness  of,  259. 
Zeus,  unity  of  content  of  the  Homeric, 

US- 


r  I AHE  following  pages  contain  advertisements  of  a  few 
of  the  Macmillan  publications  on  kindred  subjects 


What  is  Pragmatism? 

BY  JAMES  BISSETT  PRATT,  PH.D. 

Assistant  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Williams  College ;  Author  of 
"The  Psychology  of  Religious  Belief,"  etc. 

Cloth,  izmo,  $1.25  net;  by  mail,  $1.35 

The  controversy  over  Pragmatism  is  one  of  the  most  important 
movements  in  contemporary  philosophy.  Pragmatism  has  the 
double  significance  of  skill,  activity,  method  and  system  in  affairs, 
and  of  objectional  activity,  officiousness,  fussiness,  etc.  In  the  liter- 
ature of  philosophy  it  deals  with  a  skilled  method  of  analyzing  ques- 
tions which  are  fundamental  for  both  our  philosophical  and  our 
religious  conceptions.  Although  the  pragmatists  have  several  times 
presented  their  side  of  the  question  to  the  public,  no  book  has  as 
yet  appeared  in  English  written  from  the  non-pragmatist's  point  of 
view  and  giving  anything  like  a  connected  and  complete  statement 
of  his  position.  To  do  this  is  Professor  Pratt's  aim  in  the  present 
volume. 

Throughout  the  book  the  author's  first  endeavor  has  been  to  give 
a  just  and  sympathetic  presentation  of  the  chief  doctrines  of  Prag- 
matism, and  then  to  analyze  each  of  them  in  turn  so  that  its  exact 
meaning  may  become  perfectly  clear  even  to  the  non-technical 
reader.  Finally  he  has  sought  to  show  the  bearings  of  these  prag- 
matic principles  upon  the  great  questions  of  the  nature  of  man  and 
the  religious  view  of  the  universe.  The  reader  is  thus  enabled  to 
see  exactly  what  this  new  philosophy  means  and  what  it  involves, 
to  understand  the  position  of  its  opponents,  and  to  judge  for  him- 
self between  them. 

Dr.  Pratt  has  a  style  which  in  its  directness  and  simplicity  com- 
pares with  that  of  the  leading  American  prophet  of  Pragmatism, 
Professor  James,  and  his  little  book  is  so  clear  and  convincing,  so 
straightforward  and  free  from  metaphysical  cant,  that  it  should  find 
its  largest  audience  outside  of  academic  circles,  among  people  who 
want  to  know  in  plain  terms  just  what  Pragmatism  means. 


THE   MACMILLAN  COMPANY 

Publisher*  64-66  Fifth  Avenue  New  Tork 


The  Persistent  Problems  of  Philosophy 

An  Introduction  to  Metaphysics  through  the  Study  of  Modern  Systems 
BY  MARY  WHITON  CALKINS 

Professor  of  Philosophy  and  Psychology  in  Wellesley  College 
Published  in  New  York,  1907.    Second  edition,  1908 

Cloth,  8vo,  575  pages,  $2.50  net 

This  book  is  intended  for  beginners  in  philosophy  as  well  as  for 
students  and  readers  who  are  seriously  concerned  with  the  problems 
of  the  subject.  It  combines  the  essential  features  of  an  Introduction 
to  Metaphysics  with  those  of  a  History  of  Modern  Philosophy. 
Expositions  are  supported  by  exact  quotations  from  philosophical 
texts,  and  by  this  means  it  is  hoped  to  impress  upon  students  the 
necessity  of  a  first-hand  study  of  philosophical  texts.  The  classifica- 
tion of  philosophical  systems  has  been  simplified  by  the  careful 
distinction  between  "  qualitative  "  and  "  numerical "  forms  of  mon- 
ism and  pluralism.  The  Appendix  contains  brief  biographies  of 
philosophers  and  topically  arranged  bibliographies,  not  only  of  the 
philosophers  discussed  in  the  body  of  the  book,  but  also  of  the  less 
important  modern  schools  and  writers.  The  concluding  chapter, 
on  Contemporary  Philosophical  Systems,  with  the  corresponding 
part  of  the  Appendix,  offers  a  useful  summary  of  the  doctrines  of 
writers  so  recent  that  they  are  not  considered  m  most  text-books  of 
modern  philosophy. 

Though  mainly  expository  and  critical,  the  book  is  written  "  from 
the  standpoint  of  a  metaphysical  system  fairly  well  defined."  This 
is  the  doctrine  of  monistic  personal  idealism,  based,  however,  on 
experience,  and  therefore  proof  against  the  pragmatist's  attack  upon 
realistic  forms  of  absolute  idealism. 

"  It  is  exceptional  in  lucidity,  candor,  and  the  freshness  with  which 
it  surveys  well-worn  doctrines.  More  than  any  Introduction  to 
Philosophy  with  which  I  am  acquainted,  it  will  induce  its  reader  to 
turn  to  the  original  sources,  and  to  find  pleasure  in  seeing  Philo- 
sophy as  it  rises  in  the  minds  of  the  great  thinkers.  While  the 
book  is  unusually  attractive  in  style,  and  well  fitted  for  popular  use, 
it  is  the  work  of  an  original  and  critical  scholar.  The  temper  with 
which  the  history  of  philosophy  should  be  studied  finds  here  ad- 
mirable expression."  —  Prof.  G.  H.  Palmer,  Department  of  Phi- 
losophy, Harvard  University. 


THE   MACMILLAN  COMPANY 

Publishers  64-66  Fifth  Avenue  New  York 


A   LIST   OF   MACMILLAN  PUBLICATIONS  ON 
PHILOSOPHY. 


A  Student's  History  of  Philosophy.  By  ARTHUR  KENYON  ROGERS,  Pro- 
fessor  of  Philosophy  in  Butler  College.  Published  in  New  York,  1901. 
Second  edition,  1907.  Cloth,  $11  pp.,  Svo,  $2.00  net 

A.  History  of  Philosophy.  With  Especial  Reference  to  the  Formation  and 
Development  of  its  Problems  and  Conceptions.  By  Dr.  W.  WlNDEL- 
BAND,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Strassburg.  Authorized 
translation  by  James  H.  Tufts,  Ph.D.,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  the  Uni- 
versity of  Chicago.  Published  in  New  York,  1893.  Second  edition,  revised 
and  enlarged,  1901.  Latest  reprint,  1907.  Cloth,  726  pp.,  Svo,  fooo  net 

• 

An  Introduction  to  Philosophy.  By  GEORGE  STEWART  FULLERTON,  Pro- 
fessor  of  Philosophy  in  Columbia  University.  Published  in  New  York, 
1906.  Reprinted,  1908.  Cloth,  322  pp.,  izmo,  $ij6onet 

The  Persistent  Problems  of  Philosophy.  An  Introduction  to  Metaphysics 
through  the  Study  of  Modern  Systems.  By  MARY  WHITON  CALKINS. 
Professor  of  Philosophy  and  Psychology  in  Wellesley  College.  Published 
in  New  York,  1907.  Second  edition,  1908.  Cloth,  575  pp.,  Svo,  $2.50  net 

Introduction  to  Philosophy.  By  WILLIAM  JERUSALEM,  Lecturer  in  Philoso- 
phy and  Pedagogy  at  the  University  of  Vienna.  Translated  from  the  fourth 
edition  by  Charles  F.  Sanders.  Published  hi  New  York,  1910. 

Cloth,  319  pp.,  I2mo, 


An  Introduction  to  Systematic  Philosophy.  By  WALTER  T.  MARVIN,  Ph.D. 
Published  in  New  York,  1903.  Cloth,  512pp.,  Svo, 


A  Brief  Introduction  to  Modern  Philosophy.  By  ARTHUR  KENYON  ROGERS, 
Ph.D.    Published  in  New  York,  1899.    Latest  reprint,  1909. 

Cloth,  j6o  pp.,  latno,  $J.2j  net 


English  Philosophy.  A  Study  of  its  Method  and  General  Development  By 
THOMAS  M.  FORSYTH.  Published  in  London,  1910. 

Cloth,  231  pp.,  Svo,  I/7J-  net 

Dogmatism  and  Evolution.  Studies  in  Modem  Philosophy.  By  THEODORE 
DE  LACUNA,  Ph.D.,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Bryn  Mawr  College,  and 
GRACE  ANDRUS  DE  LACUNA,  Ph.D.  Published  in  New  York,  1910. 

Cloth,  259  pp.,  Svo,  %i.js  tut 


Outlines  of  Metaphysics.  By  JOHN  S.  MACKENZIE,  M.A.,  Glasgow  ;  Litt.D., 
Cambridge.  Published  in  London,  1902.  Second  edition,  1906. 

Cloth,  175  pp.,  iamo,  $1.10  net 

A  System  of  Metaphysics.  By  GEORGE  STEWART  FULLERTON,  Professor 
of  Philosophy  in  Columbia  University.  Published  in  New  York,  1904. 

Cloth,  627  pp.,  Svo,  $4.00  net 

Elements  of  Metaphysics.  By  A.  E.  TAYLOR,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in 
McGill  University,  Montreal.  Published  in  New  York,  1907. 

Cloth,  419  pp.,  Svo,  $260  net 

Concepts  of  Philosophy.  In  Three  Parts.  Part  I,  Analysis.  Part  II,  Syn- 
thesis. a.  From  Physics  to  Sociality,  b.  From  Sociality  to  Religion. 
Part  III,  Deductions.  By  ALEXANDER  THOMAS  ORMOND.  Published 
in  New  York,  1906.  Cloth,  722  pp.,  Svo,  $4,00  net 

The  Problems  of  Philosophy.  By  HARALD  HOFFDING.  Translated  by 
Galen  M.  Fisher.  With  a  preface  by  William  James.  Published  in  New 
York,  1905.  Reprinted,  1906.  Cloth,  201  pp.,  i6mo,  $r,oo  net 

What  is  Pragmatism?  By  JAMES  BISSETT  PRATT,  Ph.D.,  Assistant  Pro- 
fessor  of  Philosophy  in  Williams  College.  Published  in  New  York,  1909. 

Cloth,  256  pp.,  I2mo, 


Studies  In  Humanism.  By  F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER,  M.A.,  D.Sc.  Published  in 
London,  1907.  Cloth,  492  pp.,  Svo,  $j.sj  net 

Riddles  of  the  Sphinx.  A  Study  in  the  Philosophy  of  Humanism.  By  F.  C.  S. 
SCHILLER.  Published  in  London,  1910.  Cloth,  f]8pp.,  Svo,  $3.00  net 

The  Critical  Philosophy  of  Immanuel  Kant.    By  EDWARD  CAIRD,  LL.D, 

Professor  of  Moral  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Glasgow.     Published 

in  Glasgow,  1889.    Second  edition,  1908.  Two  volumes.     Cloth,  Svo 

Vol.  I,  654  pp.    Vol.  II,  660  pp.  The  set,  $6.25  net 

The  Philosophy  of  Kant  Explained.  By  JOHN  WATSON,  M.A.,  LL.D.,  Pro- 
fessor of  Moral  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Queen's  College,  Kingston, 
Canada.  Published  in  Glasgow,  1908.  Cloth,  515  pp.,  Svo,  $3.7$  net 

The  Philosophy  of  Kant.  As  contained  in  Extracts  from  His  Own  Writings. 
Selected  and  translated  by  JOHN  WATSON,  LL.D.,  Professor  of  Moral 
Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Queen's  College,  Kingston,  Canada.  Pub- 
lished in  Glasgow,  1888.  Second  edition,  1908. 

Cloth,  j^6  pp.,  I2mo,  $1.75  net 


The  World  and  the  Individual.  Gifford  Lectures  delivered  at  University  of 
Aberdeen.  By  JOSIAH  ROYCE.  Ph.D.,  Professor  of  the  History  of  Philos- 
ophy in  Harvard  University. 

Part  I,  The  Four  Historical  Conceptions  of  Being. 

Cloth,  588 pp.,  iamo, 
Part  II,  Nature,  Man,  and  the  Moral  Order. 

Cloth,  480 pp.,  I2TM, 

Published  in  New  York,  1899.    Third  reprint,  1908. 

The  World  a  Spiritual  System.  An  Outline  of  Metaphysics.  By  JAMES  H. 
SNOWDEN.  Published  in  New  York,  1910.  Cloth,  ji6 pp.,  i2tno,  $1.50  net 

Modern  Thought  and  the  Crisis  in  Belief.  By  R.  M.  WF.NLEY.  of  the  Uni- 
versity of  Michigan.  Published  in  New  York,  1910. 

Cloth.,  364  pp.,  I2mo,  $f.jO  net 

* 

From  Epicurus  to  Christ.  A  Study  in  the  Principles  of  Personality.  By 
WILLIAM  DE  WITT  HYDE,  President  of  Bowdoin  College.  Published  in 
New  York,  1904.  Third  reprint,  1908.  Cloth,  285  pp.,  rzmo,  fcr.jo  net 

The  Religions  Conception  of  the  World.  An  Essay  in  Constructive  Philos- 
ophy. By  ARTHUR  KENYON  ROGERS,  Ph.D.,  Professor  of  Philosophy  in 
Butler  College.  Published  in  New  York,  1907. 

Cloth,  284pp.,  Z2mo,  $1.50  net 

The  Library  of  Philosophy.    Edited  by  J.  H.  MUIRHEAD,  LL.D. 

Erdmann.  History  of  Philosophy.  Three  Volumes.     Cloth,  8vo,  $10.50  net 
Bosanquet.    History  of  ^Esthetic.  Cloth,  8vo,  $2.7$  net 

P/leiderer.    Development  of  Rational  Theology  in  Germany  and  in  Great 

Britain  since  Kant  Cloth,  8vo,  $2.75  net 

Sonar.    Philosophy  and  Political  Economy  in  Some  of  their  Historical 

Relations.  Cloth,  8vo,  $2.75  net ' 

Bradley.    Appearance  and  Reality.  Cloth,  8vo,  $2.75  net 

Ritchie.     Natural  Rights.  Cloth,  8vo,  $2.75  net 

Sifwart.    Logic:   Two  volumes  —  Vol.  I,  The  Judgment,  Concept,  and 

Inference.    VoL  II,  Logical  Methods.  Cloth,  8vo,  $5.50  net 

Stout.    Analytic  Psychology.    Third  edition.    Two  volumes. 

Cloth,  8vo,  $5.50  net 

Albee.    History  of  English  Utilitarianism.  Goth,  8vo,  $2.75  net 

Villa.    Contemporary  Psychology.  Cloth,  8vo,  $2.75  net 

Baldwin.    Thought  and  Things.  Cloth,  Svo,  two  vols.,  each  $2.75  net 

Urban.    Valuation :  its  Nature  and  Laws.  Cloth,  Svo,  $2.75  net 

Pillsbury.    Attention.  Cloth,  Svo,  $2.75  net 

Berfson.    Time  and  Free  Will.    Matter  and  Memory. 

Cloth,  Svo,  each  $2.75  net 
Baillie.    HBGEL'S  Phenomenology  of  Mind. 

Cloth,  Svo,  two  vols.,  tack  $2.75  net 


W^QU^fc-i. 

*~*-~£~^      (jr^ 


a 


xxNjtsI^        A.  //^^          * 


i    **-v-C      U     \~*^ 

n 


t