Skip to main content

Full text of "Two lectures on theism: delivered on the occasion of the sesquicentennial celebration of Princeton university"

See other formats


LIBRARY  OF  CONGRESS. 


Chap... Copyright  No. 

Shelf3D_555 

M 

UNITED  STATES  OF  AMERICA. 


TWO  LECTURES  ON  THEISM 


PRINCETON    LECTURES. 

A   series  of  volumes  containing  the   notable  lectures  de- 
livered on  the  occasion  of  the  Sesquicentennial 
celebration  of  Princeton  University. 

The  French  Revolution  and  English  Literature.    Six  Lectures. 

By  Prof    Edward  Dowden,  Trinity  College,  Dublin. 
Theism.     Two  Lectures.     By  Prof.  Andrew  Seth,  University  of 
Edinburgh 

The  Discharge  of  Electricity  in  Gases.    Four  Lectures.    By  Prof. 

J.  J.  Thomson,  University  of  Cambridge. 
The  Mathematical  Theory  of  the  Top.    Four  Lectures.    By  Prof 
Felix  Klein,  University  of  Gottingen. 

The  Descent  of  the  Primates.    By  Prof.  A.  A.  W.  Hubrecht, 

University  of  Utrecht. 

The  Nature  and  Origin  of  the  Noun  Genders  in  the  Indoger- 
manic  Languages.  By  Prof.  Karl  Brugmann,  University  of 
Leipsic 

The  Claims  Of  the  Old  Testament.  Two  Lectures  By  Prof. 
Staxley  Leathes,  D.D.,  King's  College,  London. 


TWO  LECTURES   ON 
THEISM 


DELIVERED    ON    THE    OCCASION    OF    THE 

SESQUICENTENNIAL  CELEBRATION  OF 

PRINCETON   UNIVERSITY 


BY 


/ 


ANDREW    SETH,  M.A.,   LL.D. 
n 

Professor  op  Logic  and  Metaphysics  in 
the  University  op  Edinburgh 


*v 


v 


/ 


^ 


s 


NEW  YORK 
CHARLES   SCRLBNER'S   SONS 

1897 


T& 


Copyright,  1897, 
By  Chakles  Scribner's  Sons 


SJnttoersitg  ^ress: 
John  Wilson  and  Son,  Cambridge,  U.S.  A, 


TWO  LECTURES  ON  THEISM 
I 

Theee  are  three  terms,  not  perhaps  very  clearly 
defined,  —  perhaps  not  employed  by  different 
writers  with  any  strict  uniformity  of  usage,  — 
still,  terms  which  may  suffice  to  indicate  at  the 
outset  the  possible  lines  in  which  theories  of  the 
divine  may  move.  The  terms  I  mean  are  Pan- 
theism, Deism,  and  Theism.  There  is  a  certain 
differentiation  between  them,  even  in  current 
usage.  Pantheism  either  identifies  God  with  the 
world  of  men  and  things,  or,  in  the  emphasis 
it  lays  upon  the  divine  as  the  only  reality, 
reduces  the  facts  of  finite  existence  to  a  mere 
show  or  appearance.  Pantheism  in  its  varied 
forms  moves  between  these  two  extremes ;  but 
the  feature  common  to  both  is  the  denial  of  a 
distinction  between  God  and  the  world.  In  the 
one  case,  God  is  explicitly  equated  with  the 
world-process,  so  that  there  can  be  no  talk  of 
difference ;  in  the  other  case,  we  are  taught  that 
the  difference  is  only  a  difference  that  seems. 
1 


2  THEISM 

Over  against  pantheism,  in  either  of  its  phases, 
stands  the  view  which  I  have  called  Deism. 
Deism  lays  so  much  stress  on  the  difference,  or, 
as  it  is  here  technically  called,  the  transcendence, 
of  the  divine  existence,  that  it  removes  God  out 
of  the  world  altogether,  and  sets  him  at  a  dis- 
tance alike  from  the  play  of  nature's  laws  and 
the  thoughts  and  actions  of  mankind,  —  a  spirit 
beyond  the  stars,  a  being  who  created  the  world 
once  upon  a  time,  who  may  interfere  at  times 
with  the  machinery,  but  who  contents  himself 
on  the  whole  with  "  seeing  it  go."  This  view, 
though  repudiated  by  religious  feeling  and  by 
the  more  profound  theological  thinkers,  is  em- 
bedded in  a  great  deal  of  popular  theology  and 
popular  religion.  And  in  more  prosaic  ages  of 
thought  it  is  sure  to  predominate,  to  the  exclu- 
sion or  neglect  of  the  truth  for  which  pantheism 
contends.  The  deistic  God,  an  Eire  supreme  or 
Great  First  Cause,  is  the  kind  of  God  whose  exist- 
ence the  so-called  "proofs  of  the  existence  of 
God"  are  intended  to  establish.  People  even 
speak  in  this  connection  of  proving  the  existence 
of  a  God,  —  a  phrase  which  obviously  implies 
that  they  think  of  God  as  an  individual  among 
other  individuals,  and  therefore  as  a  finite  being 
within  the  universe  in  the  widest  sense  of  that 


THEISM  3 

term.  This  is  of  course  seen  to  be  impossible,  as 
soon  as  speculation  rouses  itself.  Monotheism, 
conceived  in  this  deistic  fashion,  is  a  survival  of 
polytheistic  belief,  —  a  higher  development,  no 
doubt,  but  not  different  in  kind. 

There  is  a  certain  amount  of  authority  for  the 
use  of  the  term  Theism  to  indicate  a  view  which 
endeavors  —  whether  it  succeeds  or  not  is  another 
question,  but  which  at  least  endeavors  —  to  recog- 
nize both  immanence  and  transcendence,  and  so  to 
do  justice  to  the  truths  which  underlie  the  one- 
sided extremes  of  pantheism  and  deism.  The 
elements  which  must  be  combined  in  a  theistic 
doctrine  which  shall  satisfy  both  the  head  and 
the  heart  —  both  the  speculative  and  the  practi- 
cal reason  —  can  only  be  appreciated  after  some 
consideration  of  the  contrasted  extremes  which 
it  endeavors  to  mediate  between,  or,  as  the 
phrase  runs,  to  combine  in  a  higher  unity. 

The  contrasts  exhibit  themselves  to  some 
extent  on  the  stage  of  history,  when  we  look  at 
the  course  of  modern  philosophy.  All  historical 
generalizations  of  this  kind  require  modification, 
when  we  look  into  the  detailed  history  of  the 
time ;  they  are  in  the  main  simply  suggestive 
points  of  view,  and  I  am  far  from  desiring  to 
press  unduly  the  view  of  the  course  of  modern 


4  THEISM 

speculation  which  I  am  about  to  propound,  in 
face  of  the  exceptions  which  any  one  so  inclined 
might  produce  against  it.  Still,  it  is  not  uncom- 
mon in  the  best  histories  of  philosophy  to  regard 
the  seventeenth  century  as  an  age  of  universal- 
ism,  followed  in  the  eighteenth  century  by  a 
swing  of  the  pendulum  to  the  opposite  extreme 
of  individualism.  Universalism,  in  this  philo- 
sophic use  of  the  term,  implies  a  tendency  to 
pantheism.  Individualism  means,  in  its  first 
stage,  deism,  —  an  individually  separate  first 
cause,  as  the  originator  of  the  finite  individu- 
alities whose  reality  demands  explanation.  The 
difficulties  which  deism  encounters  in  its  search 
for  such  a  God  lead  on  this  line  of  thought 
towards  an  atheistic  culmination.  The  astron- 
omer sweeps  the  heavens  with  his  telescope  and 
finds  no  God ;  reason  finds  it  impossible  to  stop 
anywhere  in  the  infinite  regress  of  finite  or  phe- 
nomenal causes.  The  proposal  to  prove  by  the 
scientific  law  of  causality  the  existence  of  an 
uncaused  being  seems,  indeed,  little  better  than 
a  contradiction  in  terms.  Hence  the  deistic  God 
is  at  last  discarded  as  a  hypothesis  which  is  not 
required. 

Something  like  this  development  reaHy  took 
place   in  modern  thought,   if   we  look   only   at 


THEISM  5 

its  main  currents.  Seventeenth-century  thought 
may  be  said,  without  injustice,  to  culminate  in 
the  great  pantheistic  system  of  Spinoza.  This 
was  what  the  Cartesian  era  issued  in.  And  that 
this  speculative  strain  is  by  no  means  to  be 
attributed  solely  to  the  exceptional  individuality 
of  Spinoza,  as  a  man  and  a  thinker,  is  conclu- 
sively shown  by  the  development  of  the  same 
tendency  independently  by  Malebranche,  a  Chris- 
tian priest.  Malebranche  refers  to  Spinoza  with 
virtuous  indignation  as  a  miserable,  just  as  Locke, 
the  individualist  and  deist,  disclaims  all  kindred 
with  his  "justly  decried"  name,  or  as  Hume, 
the  individualistic  sceptic,  refers,  with  less  excuse, 
to  "  that  famous  atheist "  and  his  "  hideous 
hypothesis"  (Treatise,  Bk.  I.  Part  4).  Male- 
branche's  system  differs  from  Spinoza's,  no 
doubt,  in  some  not  unessential  points,  where  his 
Christian  consciousness  makes  itself  felt ;  and  his 
intention  is  unquestionably  theistic.  But,  in  the 
main  determinations  of  their  systems,  the  Father 
of  the  Oratory  and  the  excommunicated  Jew 
coincide  so  closely  that  it  is  plain  both  are 
upborne  by  a  common  stream  of  tendency  in  the 
thought  of  the  time. 

Locke  and  Leibnitz  were  the  minds  who  chiefly 
shaped  the  thought  of  the  eighteenth  century. 


6  THEISM 

The  activity  of  both  carries  us  back  some  dis- 
tance into  the  seventeenth,  just  as  the  shaping 
forces  of  the  nineteenth  begin  to  show  them- 
selves a  good  many  years  before  1800.  Leib- 
nitz's system  is  a  rehabilitation  of  the  rights  of 
the  individual  life  against  the  all-devouring 
pantheism  of  Spinoza.  Leibnitz  himself  was 
too  profoundly  speculative  a  mind  to  find  the 
last  word  of  philosophy  in  a  doctrine  of  bare 
Pluralism,  that  is,  to  accept  a  number  of  indi- 
vidual reals  as  absolutely  self-subsistent  and 
mutually  independent.  He  endeavored  to  em- 
brace them  within  the  unity  and  harmony  of 
a  single  system ;  and,  in  thus  rendering  justice 
to  the  truth  which  the  universalistic  systems 
emphasize,  went  so  far  sometimes  in  his  expres- 
sions as  to  lay  himself  open  to  the  imputation 
of  Spinozism  at  the  hands  of  his  own  degenerate 
successors,  the  prosaic  and  shallow  philosophers 
of  the  Auf  klarung,  or  Enlightenment.  For  it 
was  the  fate  of  the  Leibnitzian  philosophy,  as 
it  was  developed  in  Germany,  to  be  gradually 
stripped  of  its  profounder  elements.  In  being 
adapted  for  popular  consumption,  it  was  reduced 
to  a  cold  and  formal  rationalism,  in  which  the 
relation  of  God  to  the  world  became  more  and 
more  external. 


THEISM  7 

On  the  other  hand,  in  England  and  in  France, 
Locke's  "Essay,"  with  its  somewhat  prosaic  com- 
mon-sense and  narrow  horizons,  was  the  philo- 
sophical Bible  of  the  century.  To  Locke  himself 
an  extra-mundane  deity  was  a  matter  of  demon- 
strative certainty,  on  the  strength  ot  the  law  of 
causation.  Such  demonstrations  were  frequent 
during  the  century ;  but  Coleridge  complains,  not 
without  reason,  that  men  had  come  to  regard  G-od's 
relation  to  the  world  in  much  the  same  light  as 
that  of  a  mason  to  his  work.  A  Demiurge  or 
world-builder  was,  in  fact,  a]l  that  such  an  argu- 
ment could  at  best  succeed  m  proving ;  and  as 
the  stable  mechanical  conditions  of  the  universe 
were  more  clearly  realized,  and  also  the  incon- 
gruity became  more  apparent  of  passing  along 
the  line  of  phenomenal  causation  to  a  non-phe- 
nomenal first  cause,  this  mechanical  deism 
easily  gave  place  to  atheism.  But  deism  was 
the  first  development.  The  first  fruit  of  Locke's 
"Essay"  in  England  was  the  historically  impor- 
tant movement  known  as  English  deism,  with 
its  so-called  "religion  of  nature."  It  was  against 
this  form  of  thought  that  Butler  directed  his 
"Analogy  of  Natural  and  Eevealed  Eeligion." 
But,  as  was  seen  in  the  well-known  case  of 
James  Mill,   this  argumentum  ad  hominem,  in- 


»  THEISM 

tended  to  drive  a  deist  back  upon  Christianity, 
was  a  double-edged  weapon,  and  might  just  as 
logically  lead  a  less  convinced  deist  to  abandon 
his  deism  for  an  atheistic  or  completely  scep- 
tical position.  This  free-thinking  English  deism 
was  transplanted  to  France  by  Voltaire,  whose 
religion,  if  any  man's,  was  based  upon  the  pure 
understanding.  Voltaire  was  as  strenuous  an 
opponent  of  atheism  as  he  was  of  Christianity. 
But  the  drift  of  empirical  philosophy  towards 
a  materialistic  atheism  went  on  apace  during 
his  lifetime  among  the  circle  of  the  encyclo- 
paedists, of  whom  Diderot  is  the  greatest  name. 
The  views  of  this  circle  were  given  to  the  world 
in  1770  in  the  Baron  d'Holbach's  once  famous 
"Systeme  de  la  Nature." 

This  book  in  the  first  flush  of  its  reputation, 
and  with  all  the  adventitious  charms  of  a  sup- 
pressed work,  fell  into  the  hands  of  the  youth- 
ful ■  Goethe  at  Strassburg.  He  tells  us  in  his 
autobiography  the  impression  which  it  made 
upon  him  and  his  friends.  "We  did  not  un- 
derstand how  such  a  book  could  be  dangerous. 
It  seemed  to  us  so  gray,  so  Cimmerian,  so  death- 
like, that  we  had  difficulty  in  enduring  its  pres- 
ence; we  shuddered  at  it  as  at  a  spectre.  Not 
one  of  us  had  read  the  book  through,  for  we 


THEISM  9 

found  the  expectations  disappointed  with  which 
we  had  opened  it.  'System  of  Nature'  was  the 
announcement,  and  we  hoped  in  consequence 
really  to  learn  something  of  nature,  our  idol. 
But  how  hollow  and  empty  we  felt  in  this 
melancholy  atheistic  half-darkness  (Halbnacht), 
in  which  the  earth  with  all  her  forms,  the 
heaven  with  all  its  constellations,  vanished. 
Matter  was  said  to  exist  from  eternity,  and  to 
be  in  motion  from  eternity;  and  through  this 
motion  —  to  right  and  to  left  and  in  all  direc- 
tions —  it  was  said  to  produce,  without  more 
ado,  the  infinite  phenomena  of  existence.  We 
might  even  have  put  up  with  this,  if  the  author 
had  really  built  up  the  world  before  our  eyes 
out  of  his  matter  in  motion.  But  apparently 
he  knew  as  little  about  nature  ^as  we  did ;  for 
after  laying  down  some  general  notions,  he 
leaves  them  at  once,  in  order  to  transform  all 
that  appears  higher  than  nature,  or  as  a  higher 
nature  in  nature,  into  a  nature  that  is  material, 
ponderable,  in  motion,  it  is  true,  but  without 
direction  or  form.  And  he  believes  that  he 
has  thereby  gained  a  wonderful  deal."  This 
was  the  meeting  of  the  old  and  the  new.  The 
highest  wisdom  of  the  declining  century  —  or 
what    gave   itself    out    as    such  —  appeared    as 


10  THEISM 

foolishness  —  "  the  quintessence  of  senility  "  are 
Goethe's  own  words  —  to  the  pulsing  life  of 
the  youth  who  was  so  largely  to  shape  the 
thoughts  of  the  corning  time. 

In  England  empiricism  developed  into  scep- 
ticism in  Hume,  while  the  orthodox  theology, 
which  had  at  first  looked  askance  at  Locke,  be- 
came more  and  more  impregnated  with  the  prin- 
ciples of  the  deism  it  had  officially  to  combat. 
And  the  century  eventually  finds  its  typical  theo- 
logical representative  in  Paley,  whose  almighty 
watchmaker  is  as  true  to  Locke's  conception  of 
deity  as  his  definition  of  virtue,  as  "  the  doing 
good  to  mankind  in  obedience  to  the  will  of  God 
and  for  the  sake  of  everlasting  happiness,"  repro- 
duces Locke's  account  of  "the  true  ground  of 
morality,  which  can  only  be  the  will  and  law 
of  a  God  who  sees  men  in  the  dark,  has  in  his 
hands  rewards  and  punishments,  and  power 
enough  to  call  to  account  the  proudest  offender." 
Thus  an  interested  or  purely  selfish  morality  — 
a  heteronomous  morality,  in  the  Kantian  phrase, 
—  is  the  natural  outcome  of  a  theory  which 
makes  God  a  merely  external  creator  and  law- 
giver. And  it  is  significant  that  when  Goethe 
sought  refuge  with  Spinoza  from  the  godless  mech- 
anism of   eighteenth-century  materialism,  what 


THEISM  11 

especially  attracted  him  was  the  disinterested- 
ness which  breathes  in  every  line  of  the  "  Ethics," 
even  to  the  culminating  sentence  which  Goethe 
quotes,  "  He  that  truly  loves  God  must  not  de- 
sire that  God  should  love  him  in  return."  That 
is  almost  certainly  not  the  whole  truth  either, 
but  at  least  it  throws  into  glaring  relief  the  mean- 
ness of  Paley's  view,  and  the  insufficiency  of  the 
theory  of  which  it  forms  an  integral  part. 

It  was  by  a  natural  instinct  that  men  turned 
in  revulsion  from  the  cramping  influences  of  the 
current  theology,  whether  orthodox  or  free-think- 
ing, to  the  great  misapprehended  Jewish  thinker. 
For  nigh  upon  a  hundred  years  people  had  talked 
about  Spinoza,  says  Lessing,  as  if  he  were  a  dead 
dog.  A  rationalistic  opponent,  not  content  with 
the  ordinary  weapons  of  controversy,  prefixed  to 
his  efforts  a  portrait  of  Spinoza  with  the  inscrip- 
tion, "Signum  reprobationis  in  vultu  gerens." 
And,  as  Goethe  humorously  adds,  the  engraving 
was  so  shockingly  bad  that  there  was  no  denying 
the  allegation.  The  casual  allusions  of  Locke  and 
Hume,  already  quoted,  are  fair  specimens  of  the 
way  in  which  Spinoza  is  usually  referred  to  all 
through  the  age  of  individualism.  Lessing,  that 
great  and  intrepid  pioneer  of  nineteenth-century 
thought  and  literature,  was  among  the  first   to 


12  THEISM 

break  the  spell.  Jacobi,  though  diametrically 
opposed  to  Spinoza's  method  and  result,  con- 
tributed by  his  publications  to  enhance  his  philo- 
sophical importance  in  the  eyes  of  the  rising 
generation.  Goethe  has  put  on  record,  in  more 
than  one  place,  the  deep  impression  which  the 
"Ethics"  made  upon  him.  The  influence  of  Spi- 
noza was  decisive  upon  the  great  German  ideal- 
ists who  developed  the  philosophy  of  Kant,  more 
especially  upon  Schelling  and  Hegel.  Empha- 
size their  minor  differences  from  him  as  they 
may,  he  is  yet  to  them  the  greatest  figure  in 
modern  philosophy.  Instead  of  his  atheism 
Hegel  talks  of  his  Akosmism,  just  as  Novalis 
speaks  of  him  as  a  God-intoxicated  man.  Through 
these  and  other  post-Kantian  systems,  the  univer- 
salistic  strain  became  once  more  dominant  in 
modern  philosophy,  while  through  Schleierma- 
cher  the  same  influence  made  itself  powerfully 
felt  in  theology.  Schleiermacher's  eloquent  apos- 
trophe is  well  known,  in  which  he  calls  upon  all 
true  men  to  "  offer,  as  in  the  ancient  fashion,  a 
lock  of  hair  to  the  manes  of  the  holy  and  excom- 
municated Spinoza.  The  sublime  spirit  of  the 
universe  penetrated  him ;  the  infinite  was  his 
beginning  and  his  end,  the  universal  his  only  and 
eternal  love." 


THEISM  13 

And  far  beyond  the  limits  of  the  schools, 
whether  philosophical  or  theological,  the  same 
movement  of  man's  mind  is  observable  at  the 
turn  of  the  eighteenth  and  nineteenth  centuries. 
In  England  it  was  the  expansive  power  of  the 
poetic  imagination  that  shattered  the  world  of 
the  prosaic  understanding,  and  communicated  to 
literature  that  sense  "  of  something  far  more 
deeply  interfused,"  which  Wordsworth,  its  noblest 
exponent,  celebrates  in  his  famous  "  Lines  com- 
posed above  Tintern  Abbey,"  — 

"  a  sense  sublime 
Of  something  far  more  deeply  interfused, 
Whose  dwelling  is  the  light  of  setting  suns, 
And  the  round  ocean  and  the  living  air, 
And  the  blue  sky,  and  in  the  mind  of  man  ; 
A  motion  and  a  spirit  that  impels 
All  thinking  things,  all  objects  of  all  thought, 
And  rolls  through  all  things." 

Wordsworth  and  Coleridge  had  had  their  con- 
versations about  Spinoza  aod  the  new  German 
philosophy  on  the  ferny  slopes  of  the  Quantocks 
and  by  the  shores  of  the  Severn-sea ;  but  to 
Wordsworth  this  insight  into  the  unity  and 
kinship  of  all  that  is,  flowed  directly,  without 
the  need  of  such  intermediary,  from  "  the  spirit 
of  religious  love  in  which  he  walked  with  Nature." 
Coleridge,  we  know,  claimed  to  have  reached  in- 


14  THEISM 

dependently  at  an  earlier  date  the  same  results 
as  Schelling ;  and  all  his  life  long  he  contemplated 
a  book  on  the  Logos,  which  was,  in  his  own  words, 
to  unite  Spinozism  and  the  mechanical  deism  in 
"  the  theism  of  Saint  Paul  and  Christianity." 1 
Shelley's  aerial  flight  carries  him  towards  panthe- 
ism pure  and  simple,  rising  at  times  to  an  enthu- 
siastic worship  of  the  Spirit  of  Beauty  in  all  that 
lives,  and  again  passing  into  that  pantheism  of  illu- 
sion which  may  verge  closely  upon  pessimism. 

"  The  one  remains,  the  many  change  and  pass ; 
Heaven's  light  for  ever  shines,  earth's  shadows  fly ; 
Life,  like  a  dome  of  many-coloured  glass, 
Stains  the  white  radiance  of  eternity, 
Until  death  tramples  it  to  fragments.  —  Die, 
If  thou  would'st  be  with  that  which  thou  dost  seek." 

But,  with  whatever  varieties  in  accent,  all  these 
poetic  voices  give  utterance  to  the  essential  truth 
that  the  divine  is  not  to  be  sought  as  a  problem- 
atical Spirit  beyond  the  stars.  God  is  revealed  to 
us  alike  in  the  face  of  nature  and  in  our  own 
self-conscious  life, — in  the  common  reason  which 
binds  mankind  together  and  in  the  ideals  which 
light  us  on  our  upward  path.  God  is  not  far 
from  any  one  of  us.  Within  us  and  around  us, 
here  or  nowhere,  God  is  to  be  found.     This  truth 

1  Biographia  Literaria,  chapter  12. 


THEISM  15 

may  be  said  to  have  remained  a  permanent  pos- 
session of  the  present  century.  Jobly  empha- 
sized by  Carlyle  and  Emerson,  it  has  gradually 
leavened  that  slow-moving  mass  of  popular  think- 
ing which  generally  lags  so  painfully  behind  the 
best  insight  of  its  own  time.  For  the  enlight- 
enment of  one  century  lives  on,  as  dogma  and 
prejudice,  to  impede  the  higher  thought  of  the 
next.  Carlyle's  running  polemic  against  what 
he  calls  "the  mechanical  system  of  thought," 
and  the  grim  irony  with  which  he  assails  the 
notion  of  "proof  of  a  God,"  —  "a  probable  God," 
—  furnish  some  of  his  strongest  passages,  while 
the  chapter  of  "  Sartor "  in  which  he  outlines 
the  counter-doctrine  of  "Natural  Supernatural- 
ism  "  is  one  of  the  most  moving  pieces  of  English 
prose. 

But  it  is  time  to  return  from  this  general  sur- 
vey of  modern  thought  to  the  more  strictly  philo- 
sophical discussion  of  the  subject.  And  in  doing 
so,  we  shall  find  our  natural  starting-point  in  the 
philosophy  of  Kant,  from  which  all  the  lines  of 
modern  speculation  may  be  said  to  radiate.  The 
great  German  idealists,  I  said,  were  under  the 
decisive  influence  of  Spinoza ;  and  they  are  some- 
times treated  as  if  they  had  simply  revived  his 
pantheism,  and  grafted  it  upon  the  Critical  phi- 


16  THEISM 

losophy  of  Kant.  That,  however,  would  be  a 
superficial  view.  The  history  of  philosophy 
shows  no  such  resurrection  of  the  body  of  a 
philosophical  system,  though  the  spirit  of  it  may 
live  again  in  another  age.  So  the  dominant  uni- 
versalism  of  Spinoza's  thought  lived  again  in 
Schelling  and  Hegel;  but  the  body  it  took  to 
itself  was  developed  under  other  auspices  and  in 
another  intellectual  atmosphere.  It  was  as  much 
the  natural  outgrowth  of  Kantianism,  as  Spinozism 
was  the  natural  outgrowth  of  Cartesianism.  And 
in  Hegel's  philosophy,  at  all  events,  the  new  uni- 
versalism  certainly  aims  at  correcting  the  defects 
of  the  old,  —  and  not  only  aims  at  doing  so,  but 
in  important  points  succeeds.  While  subscribing 
unreservedly,  as  every  speculative  mind  must,  to 
Spinoza's  fundamental  proposition,  "  Quicquid  est 
in  Deo  est,"  and  accepting  therefore  his  doctrine 
of  immanent  causality,  Hegel  differentiates  his 
own  system  from  Spinoza's,  in  that  he  defines  the 
Absolute  not  as  Substance,  but  as  Subject.  He 
endeavors,  that  is,  to  conceive  the  universe  as 
the  process  of  a  self-conscious  life,  and  not  as 
the  determination  of  a  substance  that  in  itself  is 
bare  of  all  determinations,  and  possesses,  there- 
fore, no  creative  nisus  (so  to  speak),  which  might 
explain  its  self-determination  into  the  manifold 


THEISM  17 

forms  of  the  finite  world.  Hegel  escapes  in  this 
way,  too,  the  negative  logic  of  Spinoza,  which,  by 
finding  true  reality  in  the  perfectly  undetermined, 
reduces  all  the  distinctions  of  finite  existence  to 
a  species  of  illusion.  The  process  of  history  and 
of  human  life  is  to  Hegel  eminently  real.  That 
at  least  is  his  prevailing  attitude  of  mind. 

How,  then,  did  this  new  universalism  spring 
from  the  philosophy  of  Kant?  Kant's  philos- 
ophy has  many  sides,  and  one  strain  of  Kantian 
thought  has  contributed  much  to  the  strength 
of  agnosticism  in  the  present  century.  The  sub- 
jectivity and  agnosticism  which  cling  to  Kant's 
doctrine  of  knowledge  must,  however,  in  fairness 
be  regarded  as  incidental  to  the  way  in  which  he 
reached  his  main  results,  not  as  themselves  con- 
stituting his  permanently  valuable  contribution 
to  modern  thinking.  On  the  intellectual  side, 
that  contribution  undoubtedly  consists  in  his 
doctrine  of  the  categories,  —  in  the  demonstra- 
tion, to  put  it  generally,  of  a  system  of  rational 
conceptions  which  are  involved  in  every  self- 
conscious  act  of  mind,  which  enter,  therefore, 
into  the  construction  of  every  object  we  know. 
They  are  the  conditions  of  the  very  possibility  of 
experience  as  such,  and  may  be  regarded,  there- 
fore, as  the  irreducible  essence  of  the  rational 
2 


18  THEISM 

world.  Kant  himself  did  not  give  a  complete 
list  or  an  exhaustive  account  of  these  concep- 
tions, nor  can  he  be  said  to  have,  in  all  cases, 
treated  satisfactorily  their  relation  to  one  another 
and  to  the  supreme  unity  of  self-consciousness 
whose  forms  they  are.  But  he  named  the  most 
important,  and  bequeathed  to  his  successors  the 
fruitful  idea  of  an  organized  system  —  an  organ- 
ism —  of  reason. 

Kant  himself  regarded  the  categories  as  merely 
subjective,  as  a  necessary  equipment  of  human 
understanding  if  we  are  to  have  experience  at 
all,  bat  still  merely  a  subjective  mould,  as  it 
were,  into  which  we  run  the  fluid  and  form- 
less material  of  sensation,  —  something,  in  short, 
contributed  by  the  subject  in  the  act  of  knowl- 
edge, and  therefore  of  essentially  limited  validity, 
not  predicable  of  reality  as  such.  But  such 
mere  subjectivity  is,  in  the  very  nature  of  the 
case,  impossible  to  prove.  Even  if  our  cate- 
gories were  purely  subjective,  it  is  impossible 
we  should  ever  come  to  know  it;  and  the  idea  of 
a  world  of  things  in  themselves,  apart  from  the 
world  we  know,  may  easily  be  shown  to  dissolve 
in  contradictions.  A  world,  real  and  independent 
of  the  individual's  transient  acts  of  knowledge,  is 
not  a  world  divorced  from  intelligence  altogether. 


THEISM  19 

The  fact,  therefore,  that  a  category  lives  subjec- 
tively in  the  act  of  the  knowing  mind  is  no  proof 
that  the  category  does  not  at  the  same  time  truly 
express  the  nature  of  the  reality  known.  It 
would  be  so  only  if  we  suppose  the  knowing  sub- 
ject to  stand  outside  of  the  real  universe  alto- 
gether, and  to  come  to  inspect  it  from  afar  with 
mental  spectacles  of  a  foreign  make.  In  that 
case,  no  doubt,  the  forms  of  his  thought  might 
be  a  distorting  medium.  But  the  case  only  re- 
quires to  be  stated  plainly  for  its  inherent  ab- 
surdity to  be  seen.  The  knower  is  in  the  world 
which  he  comes  to  know,  and  the  forms  of  his 
thought,  so  far  from  being  an  alien  growth  or  an 
imported  product,  are  themselves  a  function  of 
the  whole.  As  a  French  writer 1  puts  it,  "  con- 
sciousness, so  far  from  being  outside  reality,  is 
the  immediate  presence  of  reality  to  itself  and 
the  inward  unrolling  of  its  riches."  When  this 
is  once  grasped,  the  idea  of  thought  as  a  kind  of 
necessary  evil  —  Kant  really  treats  it  as  such  — 
ceases  to  have  even  a  superficial  plausibility. 
Unless  we  consider  existence  a  bad  joke,  we  have 
no  option  save  tacitly  to  presuppose  the  harmony 
of  the  subjective  function  with  the  nature  of  the 
universe  from  which  it  springs. 

1  M.  Fouillee,  in  his  "  L'Evolutionnisme  cles  Idees-forces." 


20  THEISM 

The  subjectivity  of  Kant's  treatment  of  the 
categories  was,  however,  incidental  to  the  scheme, 
and  was  immediately  abandoned  by  his  idealistic 
successors.  It  is  the  point  against  which  Hegel 
brings  some  of  his  heaviest  artillery  to  bear.  His 
criticism  of  Kant  in  this  respect  is  absolutely 
conclusive.  "Thoughts,"  as  he  says,  "do  not 
stand  between  us  and  things,  shutting  us  off 
from  the  things  ;  they  rather  shut  us  together 
with  them."  In  Hegel's  hands,  therefore,  the 
analysis  of  the  structure  of  thought  is,  in  his 
own  daring  phrase,  "the  exposition  of  God  as 
he  is  in  his  eternal  essence,  before  the  creation 
of  nature  or  a  single  human  spirit."  Or,  to  put 
it  perhaps  less  alarmingly,  nature  maybe  viewed, 
in  its  formal  essence,  as  a  system  of  objective 
thought,  —  a  fossilized  intelligence,  according  to 
the  phrase  which  Hegel  repeats  from  Schelling. 
The  finite  mind  elicits  these  thoughts  in  the 
process  of  experience,  and  in  doing  so  may  fitly 
be  said  to  rethink  the  thoughts  of  the  creative 
reason.  But  the  finite  mind  is  itself  an  effluence 
or  reproduction  of  that  reason.  Thought  there- 
fore shuts  us  together  with  things  because  it  is 
the  common  essence  both  of  the  subject  and  the 
object ;  and  it  is  their  common  essence  only  be- 
cause it  expresses,  on  the  intellectual  side,  the 


THEISM  21 

nature  of  God  himself,  the  ultimate  fact  within 
which  nature  and  man  are  both  somehow  con- 
tained. Hence  the  central  position  assigned  to 
logic  in  the  Hegelian  scheme;  for  logic  inves- 
tigates the  abstract  types,  the  conceptions,  of 
which  we  find  the  real  exemplifications  in  nature 
and  history.  So  that  Hegel  says  sometimes  that 
the  other  philosophic  sciences,  the  Philosophy  of 
Nature  and  the  Philosophy  of  Mind,  may  be  re- 
garded as,  so  to  speak,  an  applied  logic.  Eeason, 
or  thought,  is  not  an  accident  of  man ;  it  is  the 
presence  in  him  of  the  universal  world-reason, 
the  light  that  lighteth  every  man  that  cometh 
into  the  world.  In  virtue  of  its  presence  in  all 
men,  interchange  of  thought  becomes  possible, 
and,  with  that,  the  growth  of  society  and  all  the 
history  of  civilization,  all  these  things  being 
based  upon  a  common  system  or  organism  of 
reason.  And,  in  like  manner,  the  fabric  of  ex- 
ternal nature  becomes  transparent  and  intelli- 
gible to  the  mind,  seeing  that  it  reveals  itself 
as  the  embodiment  of  the  same  conceptions. 
"  We  recognize  in  nature's  inner  heart  only  our 
own  reason  and  feel  ourselves  at  home  there. 
Spirit  has  the  certainty  which  Adam  had  when 
he  saw  Eve.  '  This  is  flesh  of  my  flesh  and  bone 
of  my  bone.' "    Thought  is  thus  the  great  unifier  ; 


22  THEISM 

it  is  that  which  welds  God  and  Nature  and  Man 
together  as  members  of  one  whole.  To  know 
reason,  therefore,  is  to  know  God ;  the  presence 
of  reason  within  us  is  the  presence  of  God ;  the 
progressive  rationalization  of  the  world  by  sci- 
ence is  a  continuous  extension  of  our  knowledge 
of  God,  —  a  cumulative  theistic  proof,  if  it  is 
right  to  talk  of  proof  in  a  case  where  necessary 
assumption  might  better  express  the  real  state  of 
affairs. 

But  this  purely  intellectual  account  of  the 
divine,  as  a  system  of  thoughts  or  conceptions,  is 
obviously  not  in  itself  a  sufficient  doctrine  of 
God.  It  requires  to  be  supplemented  from  the 
ethical  side.  And  here  again  we  must  take  our 
start  from  Kant,  who  is  the  modern  ethicist  par 
excellence,  who  has  in  fact  founded  upon  ethics 
his  whole  positive  teaching.  The  ethical  the- 
ology in  which  Kant's  system  culminates  is,  to 
my  mind,  by  far  the  most  important  contribution 
of  modern  philosophy  towards  a  vital  theism. 
And  this  remains  true,  although  we  may  be  just 
as  little  able  to  accept  Kant's  doctrine  here  in 
the  precise  form  in  which  he  clothed  it,  as  we 
were  able  to  accept  his  theory  of  the  categories 
as  subjective  forms  of  the  human  mind.  Al- 
though he  opened  the  way  for  the  whole  course 


THEISM  23 

of  nineteenth-century  thought,  Kant  remained 
himself  in  many  particulars  a  man  of  the  eigh- 
teenth, and  in  his  ethics  we  have  to  disengage  the 
theory  from  its  eighteenth-century  vestments. 

Kant  goes  to  work  in  the  ethical  sphere  in 
much  the  same  way  as  in  the  intellectual ;  he 
sets  out  by  asking  what  is  the  condition,  or  what 
are  the  conditions,  of  the  possibility  of  ethical 
experience  at  all.  The  fundamental  condition, 
he  discovers,  is  the  unconditional  "  thou  shalt " 
of  Duty,  —  what  he  calls  the  categorical  impera- 
tive. Here  his  position  is  impregnable ;  there 
is  no  passage  from  "  is  "  to  "  ought."  Whatever 
scheme  of  ethics  we  follow,  whatever  standard 
we  adopt  as  the  touchstone  of  the  lightness  of 
an  action,  —  say  we  are  utilitarians,  for  example, 
or  even  enlightened  hedonists,  —  the  ultimate 
judgment  which  enjoins  the  realization  of  that 
standard  must  contain  an  unconditional  and  irre- 
ducible "  ought."  If  we  are  to  have  ethics  at  all, 
then,  as  a  system  of  precepts,  we  must  rest  some- 
where upon  a  categorical  imperative.  Having 
established  this  point,  Kant  proceeds  to  ask 
what  more  this  "  ought  "  involves.  First  of  all, 
"  ought "  involves  "  can."  It  is  essentially  absurd 
to  address  a  command  to  a  being  who  has  no 
power  to   conform  to  it.     The  ethical  "  ought " 


24  THEISM 

applies  not  to  the  inanimate  things  of  nature, 
which  act  according  to  laws  of  which  they  them- 
selves know  nothing ;  it  applies  only  to  beings 
who  have  the  capacity  of  acting  according  to 
the  idea  of  a  law,  that  is,  who  have  the  power  of 
determining  themselves  according  to  the  idea  of 
an  end,  —  beings  who  have  a  will,  who  are  free. 
Moral  freedom  is  therefore  the  first  implication 
or  postulate  of  the  ethical  life.  And  to  it  Kant 
adds,  in  a  somewhat  forced  and  artificial  fashion, 
the  two  other  postulates  of  God  and  immortality. 
Immortality  is  postulated  because  the  conflict 
between  the  law  of  duty  and  the  lower  self  of 
inclination  cannot  be  brought  to  a  victorious 
conclusion  within  the  present  life,  or  indeed 
within  any  finite  period  of  time.  The  perfect 
will  which  morality  demands  is  a  flying  goal, 
"  which  fades  for  ever  and  for  ever  as  we  move." 
An  infinite  progress  of  approximation  is  all  that 
the  finite  being  can  realize,  and  for  that  infinite 
progress  an  infinite  time  is  demanded.  In  other 
words,  the  ethical  being  is  necessarily  immortal. 
The  postulate  of  the  divine  existence  suffers 
most  from  the  way  in  which  it  is  introduced. 
Kant  had  resolutely  discarded  all  considerations 
of  happiness  from  his  ethical  imperative  and  his 
idea  of  the  virtuous  man.     Duty  is  to  be  done 


THEISM  25 

for  duty's  sake  alone ;  otherwise  the  act  has  no 
ethical  value  whatever.  But  though  the  moral 
man  must  take  no  account  of  happiness  in  his 
actions,  it  would  still  contradict  our  sense  of 
righteousness  and  justice  if  there  were  to  be  a 
fundamental  divorce  between  virtue  and  hap- 
piness, or  even  a  total  want  of  any  correlation 
between  them.  Correlation  of  some  sort  is  a  de- 
mand which  the  ethical  consciousness  makes  of 
the  universal  scheme  of  things.  This  is  a  postu- 
late of  morality,  in  the  sense  that  without  it  mo- 
rality would  not  be  fully  intelligible ;  without  it 
morality  would  have  no  root  in  the  nature  of 
things.  The  appearance  of  morality  would  be 
an  unexplained  intrusion  in  a  cosmos  which  took 
no  account  of  it  one  way  or  another.  The  man 
who  was  moral  in  such  circumstances  could  be  so 
only  in  a  spirit  of  stoical  despair  or  defiant  re- 
volt. If  morality  is  to  be  fully  justified,  we 
must  believe  that  in  morality  we  have  the  uni- 
verse somehow  behind  us.  But  the  system  of 
natural  causes  in  the  midst  of  which  our  present 
life  is  lived,  shows  no  inevitable  adjustment  of 
happiness  to  virtue.  The  wicked  flourish  like  a 
green  bay-tree.  "  All  things  come  alike  to  all : 
there  is  one  event  to  the  righteous  and  to  the 
wicked ;  to  the  good,  and  to  the  clean,  and  to  the 


26  THEISM 

unclean ;  to  him  that  sacrificeth,  and  to  him  that 
sacrificeth  not." 

"  Streams  will  not  curb  their  pride 
The  just  man  not  to  entomb, 
Nor  lightnings  go  aside 
To  give  his  virtues  room ; 
Nor  is  that  wind  less  rough  that  blows  a  good  man's 
barge." 

But  there  is  no  need  to  enlarge  upon  a  discre- 
pancy which  has  furnished  moralists  with  a  theme 
since  history's  dawn.  Kant's  argument  based 
upon  it  is  that  if  the  present  sensible  world 
offers  no  guarantee  of  such  adjustment,  the 
adjustment  must  be  made  in  the  interests  of 
morality  hereafter  by  a  moral  governor  of  the 
universe,  to  whom  the  sensible  world  is  only 
part  of  a  wider  scheme  of  things. 

However  important  the  truth  it  embodies, 
it  is  obvious  that  Kant's  statement  here  is  pain- 
fully bald  and  mechanical.  He  first  separates 
what  he  has  no  right  to  separate,  and  then 
brings  what  he  has  separated  externally  to- 
gether again.  God  is  not  here  directly  con- 
nected with  the  substance  of  the  moral  law ; 
he  is  not  represented  as  the  source  of  the  ideal 
which  it  sets  up  within  us.  He  is  simply,  as  it 
were,  the  official  of  the  law,  the  instrument  for 


THEISM  27 

carrying  out  the  demands  which  the  ethical 
consciousness  makes.  The  law  of  duty  is  self- 
imposed,  according  to  the  fundamental  tenet  of 
the  Kantian  ethics.  It  is  true,  Kant  afterwards 
enjoins  us,  in  his  philosophy  of  religion,  to  obey 
the  law  as  the  law  of  God.  But  there  is  no  direct 
and  inevitable  connection  between  the  two  posi- 
tions ;  for  God,  as  we  see  here,  is  treated  by  Kant 
in  the  most  extreme  deistic  fashion,  as  a  being 
entirely  apart  from  the  self  of  the  individual. 
It  is  not,  however,  as  an  external  lawgiver  that 
God  is  the  source  of  the  ethical  law  or  ideal. 
Against  that  view,  Kant  rightly  insists  on  the 
necessity  that  the  law  shall  be  self-imposed,  if  it 
is  to  carry  with  it  an  authority  against  which 
there  is  no  appeal.  He  does  not  fully  see,  how- 
ever, that  if  its  imposition  is  referred  to  the  self 
of  the  isolated  individual,  we  are  thrown  back 
into  subjectivity,  and  are  quite  as  much  at  a  loss 
as  before  to  account  for  the  authority  of  the  law, 
the  consciousness  of  absolute  obligation  which 
accompanies  it,  —  an  obligation  not  only  for  me, 
but  for  all  rational  beings.  This  authority, 
claimed  and  exercised  by  the  higher  self,  is 
only  intelligible  if  the  ideals  of  that  self  are 
recognized  as  the  immediate  presence  within  us 
of  a  spirit  leading  us  into  all  truth  and  goodness. 


28  THEISM 

The  moral  law  is  not  first  imposed  by  the  indi- 
vidual self  (in  the  theory  of  ethics),  and  then 
ratified  or  re-imposed  by  an  external  lawgiver 
(in  the  theory  of  religion).  Bather  the  two  are 
one  from  the  beginning.  God  is  the  source  and 
author  of  the  law,  but  only  in  the  sense  that  he 
is  the  higher  self  within  the  self  which  inwardly 
illuminates  all  our  lives. 

Instead  of  connecting  God  in  this  direct  way 
with  the  substance  of  morality,  Kant  gives  him 
an  external  and  instrumental  relation  to  it.  But, 
if  it  is  not  right  to  treat  a  human  being  merely 
as  a  means,  it  must  surely  be  a  false  way  of 
putting  things  to  present  God  in  this  merely 
instrumental  light.  The  undignified  nature  of 
the  position  is  enhanced,  when  it  is  seen  that  he 
is  treated  simply  as  a  means  to  the  happiness  of 
the  individual,  —  a  deus  ex  machina,  introduced 
to  effect  the  equation  of  virtue  and  happiness. 
This  is,  even  from  the  point  of  view  of  morality 
itself,  an  unfortunate  way  of  stating  the  postu- 
late in  question.  The  puritanic  preacher  of  duty 
for  duty's  sake  lapses  curiously,  we  might  al- 
most say,  into  the  hedonistic  morality  of  the 
eighteenth  century,  which  he  elsewhere  so 
strenuously  condemns.  For,  after  all,  it  is  not 
happiness   in  any  banal  sense   that   the  ethical 


THEISM  29 

consciousness  claims  as  the  wages  of  well-doing. 
It  sets  up  no  demand  that  all  its  acts  of  self- 
restraint  or  self-sacrifice  shall  be  recompensed  by 
doles  of  happiness,  —  as  if,  says  Spinoza,  men 
expected  to  be  decorated  by  God  with  high 
rewards  for  their  virtue  and  their  best  actions, 
as  for  having  endured  the  direst  slavery.  What 
the  ethical  consciousness  does  demand  is  rather, 
as  I  have  put  it,  to  feel  the  universe  behind  it,  to 
know  that  we  are  living  in  a  moral  cosmos,  where 
our  efforts  avail  somewhat,  and  where  virtue  may 
have  the  wages  of  going  on  and  not  to  die. 

It  will  be  observed  also  in  how  baldly  indi- 
vidualistic a  spirit  the  moral  order  is  here  con- 
ceived by  Kant.  I  am  far  from  being  satisfied 
with  a  universalism  which  sacrifices  the  indi- 
vidual to  the  progress  of  the  race.  As  I  have 
ventured  to  put  it  on  another  occasion,  "  even  if 
the  enormous  spiral  of  human  history  is  destined 
to  wind  itself  to  a  point  which  may  be  called 
achievement,  what  of  the  generations  that  per- 
ished by  the  way  ?  '  These  all  died,  not  having 
received  the  promises.'  What  if  there  are  no 
promises  to  them  ?  "  If  there  are  not,  this  opti- 
mism of  progress  seems  to  me  as  tragic  at  heart 
as  any  pessimism.  I  agree  with  Kant  that  the 
immortality  of  the  individual  is  necessary,  if  we 


30  THEISM 

are  to  have  a  solution  that  can  really  call  itself 
optimistic,  a  solution  that  we  can  really  embrace 
as  satisfying  in  the  largest  sense.  But  there  is  no 
reason  why  the  recognition  of  this  should  make 
us  ignore  the  solidarity  of  the  race,  and  treat  the 
individuals  in  sheer  isolation,  as  Kant  seems  here 
to  do.  If  we  can  recognize  a  moral  purpose  in 
history,  as  the  education  of  mankind  as  a  whole, 
that  gives  our  entire  ethical  conception  a  greater 
grandeur  of  outline  without  impairing  our  convic- 
tions as  to  the  destiny  of  the  individual. 

But  the  severance  of  the  individual  from  the 
life  of  the  race  is  due  to  Kant's  initial  separation 
between  the  individual  self  and  the  inspiring 
presence  of  the  divine  life.  And  it  is  finally  to 
be  noted  that,  just  because  Kant  makes  an  abso- 
lute separation  of  this  kind,  the  imperative  of 
duty  becomes  for  him  an  empty  form  without  any 
ethical  content.  It  is  an  unconditional  command, 
but  it  commands  nothing  in  particular,  because 
it  has  no  organic  connection  with  the  material  of 
moral  duty,  as  that  has  been  evolved  in  the  course 
of  history  by  the  moral  experiences  of  mankind. 
The  applicability  of  the  imperative  to  any  par- 
ticular course  of  action  becomes  a  matter  of  ab- 
stract and  somewhat  round-about  demonstration. 
This  is  the  formalism  of  Kant's  ethical  theory 


THEISM  31 

which  almost  all  his  critics  have  condemned,  and 
which  is,  in  many  ways,  the  counterpart  of  the 
subjectivity  of  his  doctrine  of  reason. 

The  advance  of  Kant's  successors,  particularly 
of  Hegel,  was  to  connect  the  ethical  as  well  as 
the  intellectual  experience  of  man  directly  with 
the  divine  life,  and  by  so  doing  to  root  Kant's 
abstract  individual  in  the  historic  life  of  human- 
ity. In  other  words,  they  universalized  the  ethi- 
cal as  they  had  done  the  intellectual  theory.  The 
progress  of  man  upwards  from  '  the  ape  and  tiger ' 
to  the  civilization  of  the  present  day,  with  its 
altruistic  and  humanitarian  ideals,  —  this  whole 
ethical  process,  with  the  customs  and  institutions 
in  which  it  embodies  itself,  its  laws,  its  public 
opinion,  its  shifting  but  ever  deepening  and 
widening  ideals  of  honor  and  chivalry,  of  hero- 
ism or  saintly  life,  of  justice  and  self-control, — 
all  this  development  can  be  rightly  understood 
only  when  regarded  as  the  progressive  unfolding 
from  within  of  an  ideal  of  goodness,  which  in 
itself  is  the  most  real  of  realities.  The  ideal  is 
not  communicated  to  all  men  in  the  same  form, 
or  to  the  earlier  ages  with  the  same  fulness  as  to 
the  later ;  for  it  is  the  nature  of  morality  to  be 
a  progress,  —  a  progress  won  by  effort.  Character 
is  not  born,  but  made ;  it  takes  shape  under  the 


32  THEISM 

pressure  of  temptation  and  difficulty.  The  ad- 
vance of  historical  study  has  long  lifted  us  above 
the  notion  of  an  abstract  conscience  promulgat- 
ing to  all  men  the  same  perfect  moral  law.  The 
content  of  the  moral  law  grows  in  every  way  from 
age  to  age.  An  age  is  not  furnished  with  more 
light  than  it  needs  to  solve  its  own  problems ; 
revelations  are  not  made  till  the  fulness  of  time 
has  come,  that  is,  till  the  hearts  and  minds  of  men 
are  prepared  by  their  previous  training  to  under- 
stand and  appreciate  the  new  truth.  If  it  were 
otherwise,  the  revelation  would  pass  uncompre- 
hended  over  the  heads  of  the  generation  to  which 
it  was  addressed.  It  would  be  as  unprofitable  as 
the  gift  of  prophesying  in  an  unknown  tongue. 
So  natural  is  this  process  of  divine  education  that 
it  seems  as  if  the  new  insight  were  wrested  by 
man  himself  from  the  void  and  formless  infinite, 
—  as  if  the  new  truth,  the  new  ideal,  were  the 
creation  of  his  own  spirit.  And  he  then  bows 
down  and  worships  himself  as  a  god  in  a  godless 
world.  These,  however,  are  but  the  two  sides  of 
the  shield  which  may  be  opposed  to  one  another 
to  all  eternity.  All  moral  and  religious  truth  is 
won  by  the  race  for  itself,  in  the  sweat  of  its  own 
moral  experience,  but  not  without  the  indwelling 
spirit  of  God. 


THEISM  33 


II 


We  considered  in  the  preceding  lecture  the 
contributions  of  Kant  and  Hegel  toward  a  the- 
istic  position,  and  we  found  that  these  contribu- 
tions were  of  the  most  fundamental  importance. 
The  idea  of  the  world  as  a  system  of  reason,  and 
the  idea  of  it  as  a  moral  order,  are  surely  the  most 
essential  constituents  of  an  adequate  conception 
of  God.  But  we  have  still  to  ask  whether  this 
contribution  constitutes  in  itself  an  adequate 
account  of  the  Divine  Being.  Does  this  phi- 
losophy —  does  Hegel  in  particular  —  carry  us 
beyond  this  conception  (so  far  abstract  and  im- 
personal) of  a  system  of  reason  and  a  moral 
order  ?  Beyond  doubt,  many  who  have  called 
themselves  Hegelians  have  believed  that  their 
master's  system  was  not  only  consistent  with 
theism,  but  was  neither  more  nor  less  than  the 
philosophical  expression  of  the  deepest  Christian 
doctrine  of  God.  It  is  certainly  possible,  there- 
fore, to  interpret  the  system  in  this  sense ;  but  it 
may  be  that  this  interpretation  relies  to  a  consid- 
erable extent  on  the  beliefs  which  the  interpreters 
bring  with  them  to  the  study  of  their  author. 
The  Hegelian  system  itself,  if  interpreted  with 


34  THEISM 

logical  consistency,  and  according  to  its  dominant 
spirit,  scarcely  seems  to  carry  us  to  such  conclu- 
sions ;  and  by  the  most  brilliant  followers  of  the 
master  they  have  been  explicitly  denied. 

The  strength  of  Hegel's  philosophy  lies,  as  we 
have  seen,  in  his  insistence  on  the  doctrine  of  im- 
manence, —  the  immanence  of  divine  reason  in 
the  world.  The  polemical  emphasis  of  the  system 
is  directed  against  the  agnostic  relativism  of  the 
Kantian  Critique  with  its  doctrine  of  the  thing- 
in-itself,  and  against  the  easy  mysticism  of  Schel- 
ling's  Philosophy  of  Identity.  Our  knowledge 
does  not  banter  us  with  shows  and  phantasms ; 
it  is  a  knowledge  of  reality,  its  result  is  truth.  In 
ultimate  terms,  it  is  describable  as  a  revelation  of 
the  nature  of  God.  God,  therefore,  is  not  an  Un- 
knowable, nor  is  he,  as  Schelling  said,  a  Neutrum, 
—  a  pure  identity  in  which  there  are  no  distinc- 
tions, and  of  which,  therefore,  we  can  make  no 
predications.  But,  in  reaction  against  this  error, 
Hegel's  gift  of  forcible  statement  led  him  into  ex- 
pressions which  seem  to  imply  a  no  less  question- 
able extreme.  In  preaching  the  truth  that  the 
Absolute  is  revealed  in  the  world  of  its  appear- 
ances, not  craftily  concealed  behind  them,  Hegel 
seems  to  pass  to  a  sheer  identification  of  the  two. 
But  while  it  is  true  that  the  two  aspects  must  be 


THEISM  35 

everywhere  combined,  —  an  absolute  which  does 
not  appear  or  reveal  itself,  and  an  appearance 
without  something  which  appears  being  correla- 
tive abstractions,  —  that  is  not  tantamount  to  say- 
ing that  the  appearance  of  the  absolute  to  itself, 
—  the  divine  life  as  lived  by  God  himself,  —  is 
identical  with  the  appearance  which  the  world 
presents  to  the  Hegelian  philosopher. 

Hegel  does  tend,  however,  in  many  of  his  state- 
ments, to  put  the  philosopher  in  the  place  of  deity, 
and  literally  to  identify  the  history  of  humanity 
with  the  development  of  the  Absolute.  But, 
surely,  although  we  may  reasonably  hold  that  the 
evolution  of  mankind,  and  the  fashioning,  by  the 
manifold  experiences  of  time,  of  spirits  fitted  to 
take  their  place  in  one  great  spiritual  common- 
wealth cannot  be  a  mere  show  or  appearance  for 
an  eternally  complete  Deity ;  though  religious 
feeling  compels  us  to  think  that  the  long  disci- 
pline  of  our  mortal  life,  its  joys  and  sorrows,  its 
sins  and  struggles  and  infinite  aspirations,  cannot 
be  indifferent  to  God  himself,  as  if  it  were  merely 
a  pageant  that  passed  before  him,  but  must  rather 
be  conceived  as  a  process  in  which  he  bears  a 
guiding  part,  a  process  whose  results  are  truly  an 
enrichment  of  his  own  life,  —  although  all  this 
may,  or  shall  we  say,  must  be  true,  yet  surely 


36  THEISM 

we  cannot  so  identify  God  with  the  process  of 
human  history  as  to  say  that  we  have  in  the  his- 
tory of  philosophy,  for  example,  the  successive 
stages  by  which  God  arrived  at  a  knowledge  of 
himself,  complete  knowledge  being  dated  from 
the  publication  of  Hegel's  works  in  the  beginning 
of  the  present  century.  What  we  really  have  is 
the  history  of  man's  repeated  attempts  to  solve 
the  problem  of  the  universe,  —  a  history  which, 
even  from  this  point  of  view,  we  may  not  un- 
reasonably expect  to  show  marks  of  progress  and 
increasing  insight ;  though,  as  I  ventured  to  say 
on  another  occasion,  even  at  the  end,  if  we  are 
honest  with  ourselves,  the  insight  is  so  dim  that 
the  title  of  absolute  knowledge  applied  to  it  has 
the  sound  of  Mephistophelian  mockery. 

It  is,  if  possible,  even  more  plainly  so  in  the  case 
of  religion.  What  is  religion,  if  not  an  attitude 
of  the  subjective  spirit  of  man  ?  We  are  here  alto- 
gether on  human  ground.  And  the  same  is  true  of 
art  and  of  history  itself,  —  the  history  of  civiliza- 
tion, of  States  and  empires.  Is  it  not  effrontery  to 
narrow  down  the  Spirit  of  the  universe  to  a  series 
of  events  upon  this  planet  ?  Can  we  believe,  as. 
Lotze  puts  it,  "  that  the  creative  cause  of  the  uni^ 
verse  issued  from  its  darkness  into  the  light  of 
manifestation  only  by  the  narrow  path  of  earthly 


THEISM  37 

nature,  and  after  having  formed  man  and  human 
life  retreated  again  into  infinity,  as  if  with  all  its 
ends  accomplished  ?  For  this  dialectical  idyll 
we  must  substitute  an  outlook  into  the  bound- 
lessness of  other  worlds,  not  with  the  vain  effort 
to  know  the  unknowable,  but  with  the  view  of 
letting  the  boundlessness  of  this  background 
mark  out  the  narrow  limits  of  the  realm  of  exist- 
ence actually  knowable  by  us."1  And  when,  in 
the  realm  of  action  and  political  history,  Hegel 
formulates  the  characteristic  thesis  of  an  absolute 
philosophy,  "  The  real  is  the  rational,"  or  tells  us 
that  the  State  is  the  divine  Idea  as  it  exists 
on  earth,  does  not  the  optimistic  verdict  sound 
again  like  hard-hearted  mockery,  when  we  turn 
our  eyes  upon  the  miserable  inadequacies,  the 
cruel  wrongs,  the  festering  sores  of  civilization 
even  at  its  best  ?  Certainly  the  State  may  be  said 
to  be  of  divine  institution,  inasmuch  as  it  is  a 
schoolmaster  to  lead  us  into  the  ethical  life  of 
self-surrender,  mutual  respect,  and  mutual  ser- 
vice, making  us  feel  ourselves  members  one  of 
another,  and  teaching  us,  if  need  be,  to  lay  down 
our  lives  for  our  native  land.  In  all  these  things, 
we  do  well  to  regard  the  fabric  of  society  and  the 
State  as  the  instrument  of  a  divine  educative  pur- 

1  Lotze,  Microcosmus,  I.  458  (English  translation). 


38  THEISM 

pose ;  but  if  we  name  it  "  the  divine  Idea  as  it 
exists  on  earth,"  surely  the  stress  must  be  laid  at 
least  equally  on  the  second  part  of  the  phrase. 
We  must  distinguish,  as  Plato  does,  between  the 
pattern  laid  up  in  heaven  of  a  perfect  common- 
wealth and  any  earthly  realization  of  it,  marred 
and  defaced  by  human  weakness  and  passions. 

The  defect  of  Hegel's  way  of  stating  things  is 
thus  that  he  apparently  refuses  to  recognize  any 
distinction  between  the  process  of  human  experi- 
ence and  what  we  may  call  the  divine  experience 
—  the  actuality  of  the  divine  life.  He  recognizes 
only  one  process,  and  one  spirit  or  subject  as 
the  bearer  of  the  process,  the  being  that  passes 
through  the  process.  At  times,  this  subject  is 
spoken  of  as  the  world-spirit,  which  is  a  meta- 
phorical expression  like  the  Humanity  of  the 
Comtists,-  gathering  up  into  unity  innumerable 
finite  individualities  ;  but  we  are  plainly  intended 
to  identify  the  world-spirit  with  the  Absolute  Be- 
ing himself,  the  spirit  in  all  spirits,  as  Hegel  some- 
times calls  him.  Now,  obviously,  if  this  identi- 
fication is  pressed,  it  is  tantamount  to  a  denial 
of  any  self-centred  divine  life,  —  any  actuality  of 
God  for  himself,  in  the  Hegelian  phrase.  There 
is  no  knowledge,  that  is  to  say,  in  the  universe, 
no  understanding  of  the  scheme  of  things  any- 


THEISM  39 

where,  more  comprehensive  than  that  which 
works  itself  out  in  laborious  patchwork  in 
this  and  the  other  human  brain.  There  is 
no  goodness,  no  justice,  no  tenderness,  save 
that  which  springs  in  the  human  heart.  This 
is  the  sense  in  which  Hegel's  doctrine  was 
developed  by  many  of  his  ablest  followers, 
those  who  are  known  as  the  Hegelians  of 
the  Left  ;  and  such  a  doctrine  differs  in  no 
essential  particulars  from  the  Eeligion  of  Human- 
ity, except  that  it  goes  metaphysically  a  step 
farther,  and  identifies  humanity  with  the  abso- 
lute ground  of  the  universe.  And,  among  English 
Hegelians  at  the  present  day,  it  is  observable 
that  this  negative  polemic  reproduces  itself  in 
certain  writers,  yielding  a  phase  of  thought  which 
may  not  unfairly  be  described  as  Hegelian  posi- 
tivism. The  doctrine  of  immortality,  or  of  any 
world  beyond  the  present,  and  the  idea  of  any 
God  beyond  what  it  calls  "  the  civilization  of 
Christendom,"  are  especially  obnoxious  to  this 
phase  of  thought. 

But,  to  my  mind,  the  deification  of  humanity 
has  only  to  be  stated  in  order  to  condemn  itself. 
When  the  matter  comes  to  this  issue,  we  have  a 
right  to  fall  back  upon  the  elemental  simplicities 
of  thought,  —  such  as  we  find,  for  example,  in  the 


40  THEISM 

Book  of  Job :  "  Where  wast  thou  when  I  laid 
the  foundations  of  the  earth  ?  Whereupon  are 
the  foundations  thereof  fastened  ?  or  who  laid  the 
corner-stone  thereof,  when  the  morning  stars 
sang  together  and  all  the  sons  of  God  shouted  for 
joy  ? "  And  it  is  not  only  the  immensities  of  space 
and  time  and  resistless  might  that  raise  this  per- 
tinent question ;  it  applies  no  less  to  the  moral 
qualities  in  which  we  recognize  the  true  great- 
ness of  our  race,  —  a  greatness  with  which  nothing 
physical  can  be  put  in  comparison.  For  the 
Positivist  is  right,  when  he  recognizes  in  the 
spiritual  nobilities  of  human  character  the  only 
fitting  object  of  adoration  or  worship ;  mere  ex- 
tent, mere  power,  however  vast,  have  nothing 
godlike  in  themselves.  "  Should  the  universe," 
said  Pascal  in  a  well-known  passage,  "  conspire 
to  crush  him,  man  would  still  be  nobler  than 
that  by  which  he  falls ;  for  he  knows  that  he 
dies,  and  of  the  victory  which  the  universe  has 
over  him  the  universe  knows  nothing."  It  is 
the  physical  universe  which  both  Pascal  and  the 
Positivists  have  in  view,  when  they  oppose  to  it 
the  conscious  life  of  man  ;  and  the  Positivists 
would  have  us  suppose  that  man,  a  physical 
creature,  outcome  of  a  physical  world,  developed, 
or  rather  actually  created,  out  of  himself  the  god- 


THEISM  41 

like  qualities  of  justice  and  mercy  and  all  the 
varied  forms  of  goodness,  crowning  himself  thus 
the  rightful  superior  of  the  godless  universe  from 
which  he  sprang. 

I  cannot  for  a  moment  accept  the  view  of  evo- 
lution which  makes  it  consist  in  this  cunning 
manufacture  of  something  out  of  nothing.  Man 
certainly  does  develop  these  moral  qualities,  and 
he  develops  them  himself,  for  only  what  is  self- 
acquired  is  a  moral  acquisition  at  all.  But  in  his 
own  strength  he  can  do  nothing.  It  is  to  misread 
the  whole  nature  of  development  to  suppose  that 
man,  as  an  isolated  finite  creature,  could  take  a 
single  step  in  advance.  Such  a  being,  supposing 
it  possible  for  such  a  being  to  exist,  would  re- 
main eternally  fixed  in  a  dead  sameness  of  being. 
What  it  was,  it  would  remain.  Development  or 
progress  is  not  the  making  of  something  out  of 
nothing,  but  the  unfolding  or  manifestation  of  that 
which  in  another  aspect  eternally  is.  It  is  possi- 
ble, therefore,  only  to  a  being  who  forms  part  of  a 
divinely  guided  process,  and  who  draws  in  conse- 
quence from  a  fount  of  eternal  fulness.  Just  as 
it  is  impossible,  therefore,  to  believe  that  there  is 
no  knowledge  in  the  universe  greater  than  that  of 
man  or  of  beings  like  him,  so  it  is  incredible  that 
there  should  be  no  Eternal  Goodness,  as  the  source 


42  THEISM 

of  those  ideals  of  which  we  are  conscious  as  the 
guiding  star  of  all  our  progress,  but  which  we  our- 
selves so  palpably  fail  to  realize. 

In  justice  to  Hegel,  it  is  only  proper  to  say  that 
it  is  precisely  his  contribution  to  a  true  doctrine 
of  evolution  which  forms  one  of  his  most  im- 
portant services  to  philosophy.  Hegelianism  has 
insisted  that  a  development  is  not  an  addition  of 
that  which  was  in  no  sense  there  before ;  con- 
sequently a  developing  series  can  only  be  under- 
stood in  the  light  of  its  highest  term.  The  true 
nature  of  the  cause  becomes  apparent  only  in  the 
effect.  All  explanation  of  the  higher  by  the 
lower,  such  as  the  naturalistic  theories  attempt, 
is  philosophically  a  hysteron  proteron,  —  a  precise 
inversion  of  the  true  account.  The  antecedents 
assigned  are  not  the  causes  of  the  consequents ; 
for  by  antecedents  the  naturalistic  theories  mean 
the  antecedents  (matter  and  energy  for  example) 
in  abstraction  from  their  consequents,  the  ante- 
cedents taken  as  they  appear  in  themselves,  or  as 
we  might  suppose  them  to  be  if  no  such  conse- 
quents had  ever  issued  from  them.  So  conceived, 
however,  the  antecedents  have  no  real  existence 
—  they  are  mere  entia  rationis  —  abstract  aspects 
of  the  one  concrete  fact  which  we  call  the  uni- 
verse.  The  true  nature  of  the  antecedents  is  only 


THEISM  43 

learned  by  reference  to  the  consequents  which 
follow ;  or,  as  I  put  it  before,  the  true  nature  of 
the  cause  becomes  apparent  only  in  the  effect. 
All  ultimate  or  philosophical  explanation  must 
look  to  the  end.  Hence  the  futility  of  all  at- 
tempts to  explain  human  life  in  terms  of  the 
merely  animal,  to  explain  life  in  terms  of  the  inor- 
ganic, and  ultimately  to  find  a  sufficient  formula 
for  the  cosmic  process  in  terms  of  the  redistribu- 
tion of  matter  and  motion. 

The  stress,  therefore,  which  Hegelianism  has 
laid  upon  the  true  interpretation  of  evolution  con- 
stitutes, as  I  have  said,  one  of  its  great  claims  upon 
our  gratitude  in  an  age  when  evolution  is  every- 
where in  the  air,  and  when  the  most  misleading 
ideas  of  its  nature  are  current.  The  interpreta- 
tion, it  is  true,  is  no  new  insight  on  Hegel's  part ; 
it  is  substantially  what  we  find  in  Aristotle. 
But  inasmuch  as  Hegel  has  incorporated  it  in 
the  very  structure  of  his  thinking  and  given  it  a 
powerful  modern  expression,  we  rightly  connect 
the  doctrine  with  his  name.  It  is  obvious,  how- 
ever, that  the  line  of  thought  which  identifies 
the  divine  source  and  goal  of  evolution  with  its 
highest  human  manifestations  —  which  believes 
that  the  Absolute  first  arrives  at  self-conscious- 
ness in  man,  and   has   no   other   self-conscious 


44  THEISM 

existence  —  falls  away  from  the  profound  Aristo- 
telian view  of  the  ivepyeia,  or  completed  actual- 
ity, as  the  eternal  prius  of  all  its  evolutionary 
phases,  and  falls  back  upon  the  naturalistic  view 
according  to  which  the  new  stage  adds  to  its 
predecessor  something  which  was  not  there  be- 
fore at  all.  The  appearance  of  man  becomes 
then  identical  with  the  creation  of  God;  man 
creates  himself,  and  at  the  same  time  brings  God 
to  the  birth.  On  such  an  interpretation,  Hegel- 
ianism  plainly  declines  upon  the  level  of  the 
purely  materialistic  theories ;  and  however  we 
may  judge  of  Hegel's  own  meaning  and  inten- 
tion, history  shows  that  this  danger  is  inherent 
in  his  method  of  statement  and  in  the  excessive 
emphasis  laid  on  the  doctrine  of  immanence.1 

The  real  explanation  of  Hegel's  sheer  identi- 
fication of  the  divine  existence  with  the  human 
process  is  doubtless  to  be  found  in  the  too  exclu- 
sive intellectualism  of  his  system.  Knowledge 
as  such  does  not  force  into  view  the  differences 
between  one  personality  and  another.  Eather, 
so  far  as  we  merely  know,  we  sink  those  cliffer- 

1  It  may  be  added  in  passing  that,  even  if  such  a  view  of 
evolution  were  competent  to  explain  the  actual  stage  reached 
by  man  in  knowledge  and  morality,  it  would  be  quite  unable 
to  explain  the  possibility  of  progress  and  the  existence  of  the 
ideal  which  guides  that  progress. 


THEISM  45 

ences,  and  occupy  what  is  called  an  objective  or 
impersonal  standpoint.  If  we  regard  the  world 
simply  as  a  system  of  thought,  as  something  to 
be  intellectually  understood  and  reproduced,  we 
all  place  ourselves  at  the  same  point  of  view. 
We  are  re-thinking  the  same  thoughts;  and  it 
becomes  not  unnatural  to  treat  the  different 
finite  thinkers  as  reproductions,  functions,  or 
modes  of  one  universal  self-consciousness.  This 
unification  of  consciousness  in  a  single  Self  is 
sometimes  carried  so  far  that  to  speak  of  self- 
consciousness  or  mind  in  the  plural  is  branded  as 
an  apostasy  from  the  only  true  philosophic  faith. 

But  any  plausibility  which  this  point  of  view 
may  possess  within  the  realm  of  pure  intellect 
vanishes  at  once  as  soon  as  we  turn  to  the  moral 
sphere ;  we  are  not  merely  contemplative  intel- 
lects, we  are,  above  all,  agents  or  doers.  It  is 
well,  as  Hegel  does,  to  insist  on  the  rational 
character  of  the  universe,  but  to  make  Thought 
the  exclusive  principle  is  either  to  fall  into  a 
one-sided  extreme  or  to  use  "  thought "  in  a  non- 
natural  sense.  Thought  cannot  fairly  be  made 
to  include  will,  and  any  theory  of  the  universe 
which  neglects  the  fact  of  will  omits  that  which 
seems  to  communicate  a  living  reality  to  the 
whole.     A  system  which,  like  Hegel's,  lays  ex- 


46  THEISM 

elusive  stress  on  thought  is  always  in  danger 
of  reducing  the  universe  to  a  phantasm  of  the 
intellect,  —  an  impersonal  system  of  thought- 
harmony,  —  or,  in  Mr.  Bradley's  vivid  phrase, 
"an  unearthly  ballet  of  bloodless  categories." 
It  is  in  the  will,  in  purposive  action,  and  par- 
ticularly in  our  moral  activity,  as  Fichte,  to  my 
mind,  conclusively  demonstrated,  that  we  lay 
hold  upon  reality.  All  that  we  know  might  be 
but  a  dream-procession  of  shadows,  and  the  mind 
of  the  dreamer  no  more  than  the  still  mirror  in 
which  they  are  reflected,  if  indeed  it  were  any- 
thing but  the  shifting  shadows  themselves.  But 
in  the  purposive  "  I  will,"  each  man  is  real,  and 
is  immediately  conscious  of  his  own  reality. 
Whatever  else  may  or  may  not  be  real,  this  is 
real.  This  is  the  fundamental  belief,  around 
which  scepticism  may  weave  its  maze  of  doubts 
and  logical  puzzles,  but  from  which  it  is  eventu- 
ally powerless  to  dislodge  us,  because  no  argument 
can  affect  an  immediate  certainty,  —  a  certainty, 
moreover,  on  which  our  whole  view  of  the  uni- 
verse depends. 

Now  the  individuality  or  self-hood  of  which  we 
are  conscious  in  willing,  is  felt  as  one  which  im- 
plies a  real  difference  not  only  between  me  and  any 
other  finite  self,  but  also  a  real  difference  or  dual- 


THEISM  47 

ism  between  me  and  the  absolute  spirit.  I  exist 
in  God.  "  The  human  soul,"  as  has  been  said,  "  is 
neither  self- derived  nor  self-existing.  It  would 
vanish  if  it  had  not  a  substance,  and  its  substance 
is  God."1  God  is  the  fountain  light  of  all  our 
day,  the  master  light  of  all  our  seeing,  inasmuch 
as  we  share  in  the  common  or  universal  reason; 
and  his  are  the  ideals  which  illuminate  and  guide 
our  life.  But  in  our  wills  we  feel  a  principle  of 
self-hood,  which  separates  us  even  from  the 
Being  who  is  the  ground  of  our  existence.  This 
is  most  manifest  in  the  sphere  of  moral  duty. 
"  Our  wills  are  ours  to  make  them  Thine,"  as  the 
poet  finely  puts  it.  But  they  must  be  really 
ours,  if  there  is  to  be  any  ethical  value  in  the 
surrender,  —  if  there  is  even  to  be  any  meaning 
in  the  process  at  all.  If  there  are  not  two  wills 
involved,  then  no  relation  between  them  is  pos- 
sible, and  the  imaginary  duality  is  an  illusion 
incident  to  our  limited  point  of  view.  But  the 
ethical  consciousness  places  its  veto  once  for  all 
upon  any  such  sophistication  of  its  primary  and 
absolute  deliverance;  and  by  that  absolute  de- 
liverance, we  shall  do  well,  I  think,  to  stand. 
The  speculative  reason  sees  no  alternative  be- 
tween absolute  dependence,  which  would  make 

1  Lord  Gifford,  quoted  by  Professor  Upton,  Hibbert  Lectures, 
p.  284. 


48  THEISM 

us  merely  the  pipes  upon  which  the  divine  mu- 
sician plays,  and  absolute  independence,  which 
would  make  the  world  consist  of  a  plurality  of 
self-subsistent  real  beings.  These  are  the  only 
kinds  of  relation  which  it  finds  intelligible.  But 
it  seems  to  me  that  it  must  be,  in  the  nature 
of  the  case,  impossible  for  the  finite  spirit  to 
understand  the  mode  of  its  relation  to  the  in- 
finite or  absolute  Spirit  in  which  it  lives.  That 
relation  could  only  be  intelligible  from  the  ab- 
solute point  of  view.  The  fact,  then,  that  we 
cannot  reconcile  the  partial  independence  and 
freedom  of  the  finite  self  with  its  acknowledged 
dependence  upon  God  in  other  respects,  need  not 
force  us  to  abandon  our  primary  moral  convic- 
tion, in  deference  to  a  speculative  theory  which 
may  be  applying  a  finite  plumb-line  to  measure 
the  resources  of  the  infinite.  After  all,  why 
should  the  creation  of  beings  with  a  real,  though 
partial,  freedom  and  independence  be  an  absolute 
impossibility  ?  It  is  certainly  the  only  view 
which  makes  the  world  a  real  place,  —  which 
makes  the  whole  labor  of  history  more  than 
a  shadow  fight  or  aimless  phantasmagoria. 

I  have  dwelt,  in  the  foregoing,  upon  the  inade- 
quacy of  any  theory  which  pushes  the  doctrine 


THEISM  x49 

of  immanence  to  the  extreme  of  absolutely  identi- 
fying the  finite  and  the  human  process.  Let  me 
exemplify,  by  a  recent  instance,  a  counter  error 
into  which  it  is  easy  to  fall.  The  first  danger  we 
found  historically  exemplified  in  the  Hegelian 
system,  or  at  least  in  important  developments  of 
Hegelian  thought.  Mr.  Bradley's  recent  work 
on  "  Appearance  and  Reality  "  may  be  regarded, 
in  many  respects,  as  an  attempt  to  supplement 
and  correct  the  defects  of  the  Hegelian  state- 
ment; and  as  it  is  without  doubt  the  most  im- 
portant metaphysical  work  which  has  appeared 
in  England  for  a  considerable  time,  I  make  no 
apology  for  using  it  in  illustration  of  the  next 
part  of  my  argument. 

Mr.  Bradley  has  always  protested  against  the 
reduction  of  the  life  of  the  world  to  a  set  of 
logical  categories ;  and  in  this  volume  he  recalls 
his  fellow  Hegelians  from  a  too  narrow  human- 
ism to  an  insight  into  the  vastness  of  the  sus- 
taining Life  that  operates  unspent  throughout 
the  universe.  The  whole  book  is  a  praiseworthy 
attempt  to  treat  the  life  of  the  Absolute  for 
itself  as  a  reality,  as  the  most  real  of  realities. 
The  truth  on  which  he  insists  may  seem  toler- 
ably elementary ;  the  strange  thing  would  rather 
seem    to    be    that   man    should    ever    forget   his 

4 


50  THEISM 

position  as  a  finite  incident  in  the  plan  of  things, 
and  measure  himself  with  the  unmeasurable 
Spirit  of  the  universe.  Is  it  not  both  absurd 
and  blasphemous  to  suppose  that  the  Power 
which  cradles  and  encompasses  all  our  lives 
is  not  itself  a  living  fact,  and  that  it  is  re- 
served for  man  to  bring  the  Absolute,  as  it  were, 
to  the  birth  ?  True  as  it  is,  in  the  proper  refer- 
ence, to  say  that  the  Absolute  realizes  itself  in 
human  self-consciousness,  the  statement  becomes 
fundamentally  absurd,  if  it  is  taken  to  mean  that 
the  Absolute  exists,  so  to  speak,  by  the  grace  of 
man,  and  lives  only  in  the  breath  of  his  nostrils. 
But  the  most  elementary  truths  are  sometimes 
most  easily  forgotten  in  the  heat  of  polemic 
against  some  particular  error.  And  therefore 
the  stress  which  Mr.  Bradley  lays  throughout  his 
volume  upon  the  necessarily  superhuman  charac- 
ter of  the  Absolute  —  its  inexpressible  and 
incomprehensible  transcendence  of  human  con- 
ditions of  being  and  thinking  —  constitutes  a 
salutary  corrective  to  a  good  deal  of  current 
speculation.  But  Mr.  Bradley  has  not  been  con- 
tent simply  to  restore  to  us  this  fundamental  in- 
sight. He  offers  us  himself  a  constructive  theory 
of  absolute  experience  —  in  vague  outline,  as  he 
often  admits,  but  still  a  constructive  theory  in 


THEISM  51 

pretty  definite  terms.  And  the  reason  why  I  call 
attention  to  this  theory  is  that  it  illustrates  so 
effectively  the  counter-error  against  which  we 
must  guard  in  forming  our  conception  of  the 
divine  nature,  —  the  pantheism  or  akosmism 
which  reduces  all  finite  experience  to  a  species 
of  illusion. 

This  goal  is  indicated  already  in  the  title  of 
the  hook  "Appearance  and  Eeality  "  ;  for  "  reality  " 
is  restricted  to  the  life  of  the  Absolute  for  itself, 
and  all  the  world  of  our  knowledge  and  experience 
is  described  as  "  appearance," — branded,  indeed,  as 
"  mere  appearance,"  "  irrational,"  "  self-contradic- 
tory "  appearance,  not  to  mention  other  deprecia- 
tory adjectives  and  terms  of  excommunication. 
According  to  Mr.  Bradley,  knowledge,  inasmuch 
as  it  is  relational  throughout,  is  defective  as  such  ; 
it  makes  distinctions  (it  distinguishes  qualities, 
for  example,  in  a  thing)  but  it  never  re- 
duces its  distinctions  to  a  real  unity.  The  very 
relation  of  subject  and  object,  which  '  must 
exist  in  every  instance  of  knowledge,  implies 
a  difference  not  overcome.  But  in  the  Absolute 
all  differences  must  be  overcome,  perfect  unity 
must  be  realized ;  there  must  be  what  is  called 
an  "all-pervasive  transfusion."  Now,  the  only 
hint  we  have  of  such  a  state,  according  to  Mr. 


52  THEISM 

Bradley,  is  in  pure  feeling  —  the  diffused  sense 
of  being,  out  of  which  our  conscious  life  seems 
continually  to  emerge.  The  first  dawn  of  active 
consciousness  introduces  the  distinctions  of  know- 
ledge into  this  characterless  unity.  Indeed, 
Mr.  Bradley  admits  that  we  hardly  possess  this 
state  of  mere  feeling  "  as  more  than  that  which 
we  are  in  the  act  of  losing."  I  would  go  farther 
and  say  more  definitely  that  it  is  a  state  which 
we  never  actually  realize,  though  we  seem  at 
times  to  approximate  to  it,  and  conceive  it  as 
being  approached  asymptotically  in  the  lowest 
forms  of  organic  life.  Such  asymptotic  approach 
consists  simply  in  dropping  one  by  one  the  dis- 
tinctions of  our  own  conscious  existence.  Con- 
sequently, the  state  is  describable  only  by  nega- 
tives, and  its  realization  would  mean  a  lapse  into 
unconsciousness  altogether. 

Be  that  as  it  may,  in  the  meantime,  this  is 
the  analogy  which  Mr.  Bradley  uses  throughout, 
in  his  attempt  to  construct  or  body  forth  the 
experience  of  the  Absolute.  It  must  be  a  higher 
experience  in  which  thought  shall,  as  it  were, 
return  to  the  immediacy  of  feeling.  "We  can 
form  the  general  idea,"  he  says,  "of  an  abso- 
lute intuition  in  which  "phenomenal  distinctions 
are    merged,   a   whole    become    immediate   at    a 


THEISM  53 

higher  stage  without  losing  any  richness  .  .  . 
a  total  experience  where  will  and  thought  and 
feeling  may  all  once  more  be  one."  But  though 
Mr.  Bradley  is  constantly  saying  that  no  rich- 
ness is  lost,  that  all  the  distinctions  are  some- 
how retained  and  preserved,  it  is  nothing  more 
than  saying.  His  own  logic,  which  stumbles 
persistently  over  the  fact  of  difference  and  re- 
lation, and  his  own  analogy  of  the  distinction- 
less  life  of  feeling,  carry  him  irresistibly  to  a 
Brahmanic  pantheism,  in  which  all  finite  ex- 
istence simply  disappears  as  an  unreal  dream. 
He  runs  riot  in  metaphors  to  describe  the  consum- 
mation of  finite  appearance  in  the  Absolute ;  and 
the  nature  of  these  metaphors  is  of  itself  suffi- 
ciently instructive.  Appearances  are  said  to  be 
"merged,"  "fused,"  "  blended,"  "  absorbed,"  "  run 
together,"  "  embraced  and  harmonized,"  "  dis- 
solved in  a  higher  unity,"  "  transformed,"  above 
all,  "transmuted."  "Transmuted"  is  the  blessed 
word  from  which  Mr.  Bradley  seems  to  derive 
most  comfort.  But  for  "  transmuted  "  we  find  at 
times  the  sinister  synonyms  "  suppressed,"  "  dis- 
solved," "  lost."  In  one  place  "  transmuted  "  and 
"destroyed"  are  expressly  coupled,  while  in  another 
we  are  told  that  the  "  process  of  correction,"  which 
finite  existence  undergoes  in  the  Absolute  mav 


54  THEISM 

"  entirely  dissipate  its  nature."  In  this  fashion, 
the  finite  self-consciousness,  among  other  things, 
is  to  be  embraced  and  harmonized  by  being 
"transmuted  and  suppressed  as  such."  Or,  as 
he  puts  it  elsewhere  with  audacious  irony,  "the 
individual  never  can  in  himself  become  a  harmon- 
ious system.  In  the  complete  gift  and  dissipation 
of  his  personality,  he,  as  such,  must  vanish."  A 
gift  of  personality  which  is  at  the  same  time  the 
dissipation  of  the  personality  in  question,  a  har- 
monizing which  means  disappearance,  recall  too 
forcibly  the  Koman  method  of  pacification,  —  they 
make  a  desert  and  they  call  it  peace. 

In  fact  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  Mr. 
Bradley's  speculation,  with  its  repudiation  of 
the  form  of  knowledge  as  such,  on  the  ground 
of  the  difference  and  relation  which  it  involves, 
leads,  not  to  any  higher  or  larger  unity,  but  to 
the  pit  of  undifferentiated  substance,  out  of 
which  Hegel  took  so  much  pains  to  dig  phi- 
losophy. The  greater  part  of  Mr.  Bradley's  book 
seems  to  me  to  reproduce  in  essence,  and  often 
almost  in  expression,  the  Spinozistic  doctrine  of 
Imagination,  which  makes  finite  existence  a 
species  of  illusion.  No  doubt  there  were  two 
tendencies  at  strife  in  Spinoza,  too;  but  his 
dominant  thought  is  that  "  all  determination  is 


THEISM  55 

negation,"  and  so  is  not  truly  real.  Hence  all 
determinations  vanish,  like  clouds  before  the  sun, 
in  the  viewless  unity  of  the  unica  substantia. 
But  if  finite  existence  is  illusory,  and  its  distinc- 
tions simply  disappear,  then  of  necessity  the 
unity  which  we  reach  by  the  denial  of  these 
distinctions  is  quite  characterless.  We  have 
illusion  on  the  one  side,  and,  as  the  counter 
stroke,  nonentity  on  the  other.  For  does  not 
Scotus  Erigena  tell  us,  at  the  end  of  a  similar 
line  of  thought,  "  Deus  propter  excellentiam  non 
immerito  nihil  vocatur  "  ? 

The  mention  of  Erigena  suggests  the  extent 
to  which  this  mode  of  reasoning  has  prevailed. 
Although  it  is  chiefly  associated  in  modern  phi- 
losophy with  Spinozism  and  the  doctrine  of 
undifferentiated  substance,  as  the  most  typical 
example  of  the  tendency,  it  dominates  not  only 
the  Brahmanic  speculation  of  the  East,  but,  from 
Philo  downwards,  has  formed  a  constant  element 
in  the  religious  philosophy  of  the  West.  Neo- 
Platonism  culminates  in  the  doctrine  of  the  abso- 
lutely transcendent  One,  "  beyond "  both  the 
sensuous  and  the  intellectual  world,  elevated 
above  all  thought,  all  being,  all  goodness,  neither 
conscious,  therefore,  nor  active ;  nameless,  and 
without  any   quality  whatsoever.      So  Plotinus 


56  THEISM 

reasoned,  while  his  followers  endeavored  to  scale 
a  still  giddier  height  in  refusing  even  to  desig- 
nate the  ineffable  as  "  One."  Iamblichus  and 
Proclus  superimposed  upon  the  One  of  Plotinus 
a  still  higher,  completely  ineffable,  principle. 
The  Neo-Platonic  philosophy  had  a  powerful 
influence  upon  Christian  thought.  It  was  re- 
vived in  the  great  system  of  Erigena  at  the 
beginning  of  the  ninth  century,  and  it  is  the 
underlying  thought  of  all  speculative  mysticism. 
Under  the  name  of  "  negative  theology,"  it  has 
continually  reappeared  in  the  higher  walks  of 
theological  philosophy ;  perhaps  its  most  recent 
and  noteworthy  reappearance  being  made  in 
Dean  Mansel's  celebrated  Bampton  Lectures, 
which  employ  the  weapons  of  agnosticism  in 
defence  of  the  churchly  faith.  I  may  be  able, 
perhaps,  before  I  close,  to  indicate  what  seems  to 
me  the  truth  which  this  negative  theology 
inaptly  expresses.  But  taken  as  it  stands,  and 
as  it  states  itself,  it  produces  the  effect  of  a 
dangerous  falsehood.  Striving  to  exalt  the 
Divine  into  a  region  beyond  thought  and  beyond 
expression,  it  leaves  us  with  nothing  in  our 
grasp  at  all.  The  Absolute  Being  becomes  a 
mere  abstraction  or,  like  Shelley's  Demogorgon, 
"a  mighty  Darkness  filling  the  seat  of  power." 


THEISM  57 

This  is  well  exemplified  in  the  conclusions  to 
which  Mr.  Bradley  is  driven.  Morality,  he 
says,  cannot,  as  such,  be  ascribed  to  the 
Absolute.  Goodness,  as  such,  is  but  appearance, 
and  is  transcended  in  the  Absolute.  Will  can- 
not belong,  as  such,  to  the  Absolute.  In  the 
Absolute  even  thought  must  "  lose  and  transcend 
its  proper  self."  If  the  term  "personal,"  he  says 
again,  is  to  bear  anything  like  its  ordinary  sense, 
then  assuredly  the  Absolute  is  not  merely  per- 
sonal. "The  Absolute,"  he  says  roundly,  "is 
not  personal,  nor  is  it  moral,  nor  is  it  beautiful 
or  true." 

What  is  the  inevitable  effect  upon  the  mind 
of  this  cluster  of  negations  ?  Surely  it  will  be 
this  :  Either  the  Absolute  will  be  regarded  as  a 
mere  Unknowable,  with  which  we  have  no  con- 
cern; or  the  denial  of  will,  intellect,  morality, 
personality,  beauty,  and  truth,  will  be  taken  to 
mean  that  the  Absolute  is  a  unity  indifferent  to 
these  higher  aspects  of  experience.  It  will  be 
regarded  as  non-moral  and  impersonal,  in  the 
sense  of  being  below  these  distinctions;  and  our 
Absolute  will  then  remarkably  resemble  the  soul- 
less matter  of  the  materialist.  Nothing,  indeed, 
is  more  certain  than  that  extremes  meet  in  this 
fashion,  and  that  the  attempt  to  reach  the  super- 


58  THEISM 

human  falls  back  into  the  infra-human.  Of 
course  Mr.  Bradley  intended  his  unity  to  be  a 
higher  and  not  a  lower  unity.  "  The  Absolute," 
he  says  in  one  place,  "  is  not  personal,  because  it 
is  personal  and  more.  It  is,  in  a  word,  super- 
personal."  And  as  if  aware  of  the  danger  that 
lurks  in  his  denials,  he  even  warns  us  that,  if 
there  is  a  risk  of  falling  back  upon  the  lower 
unity,  it  is  better  to  affirm  personality  than  to 
call  the  Absolute  impersonal.  But  there  is  more 
than  a  risk  ;  I  maintain  there  is  an  absolute  cer- 
tainty that  this  will  be  the  end. 

Hence  the  somewhat  unexpected  result  of  Mr. 
Bradley's  attempt  to  transcend  experience  and  to 
determine  the  Absolute  as  such  —  its  nature  and 
mode  of  existence  for  itself  —  is  to  throw  into 
relief  the  strong  points  of  the  Hegelian  scheme. 
The  negative  results  of  Mr.  Bradley's  search  are 
an  involuntary  confirmation  of  Hegel's  wisdom 
in  refusing  to  step  beyond  the  circle  of  know- 
ledge and  the  process  of  history.  We  have  seen 
that  Hegel's  theory  is  indefensible,  so  far  as  it 
equates  the  Absolute  with  human  experience. 
But  the  theory  is  false  only  so  far  as  it  proposes 
to  confine  the  spirit  of  the  Universe  to  these 
earthly  tabernacles.  So  understood,  I  have  urged 
that  it  cabins  the  spirit  of  man  within  a  narrow 


THEISM  59 

and  self-sufficient  positivism.  It  undermines  the 
sentiment  of  reverence,  and  dulls  our  sense  of 
the  infinite  greatness  and  the  infinite  mystery  of 
the  world.  But  it  is  profoundly  true,  so  far  as  it 
asserts  that  only  by  predicates  drawn  from  hu- 
man experience  can  we  determine  the  Absolute 
at  all,  and  that,  moreover,  such  determination  is 
substantially  and  practically,  though  doubtless 
not  literally,  true. 

For  here  is  the  core  of  truth  that  gives  vital- 
ity to  "negative  theology,"  and  ensures  its  con- 
stant re-appearance.  The  nature  of  the  existence 
which  the  Absolute  enjoys  for  itself  is,  and  must 
be,  incomprehensible  save  by  the  Absolute  itself. 
We  cannot  construct  the  Divine  life  even  in  vague 
generality,  and  that  for  the  simplest  of  all  rea- 
sons, —  we  are  men,  and  not  God.  Mr.  Bradley's 
discussion  seems  to  me  to  prove  afresh  that  the  at- 
tempt metaphysically,  scientifically,  or  literally,1 
to  determine  the  Absolute  as  such  is  necessarily 
barren.  Where  the  definition  is  not  a  mere  tau- 
tology, it  is  a  complex  of  negatives,  and  if  not 
technically  untrue,  it  has  in  its  suggestions  the 
effects  of  an  untruth.  Our  statements  about  the 
Absolute  are  actually  nearer  the  truth  where 
they  give  up  the  pretence  of  literal  exactitude, 

1  I  use  these  here  for  the  moment  as  equivalent  terms. 


60  THEISM 

and  speak  in  terms  of  morality  and  religion,  ap- 
plying to  it  the  characteristics  of  our  highest 
experience.  Such  language  recognizes  itself  in 
general  (or  at  least  it  certainly  should  recognize 
itself)  as  possessing  only  symbolical  truth,  —  as 
being  in  fact  "  thrown  out,"  as  Matthew  Arnold 
used  to  say,  at  a  vast  reality.  But  both  religion 
and  the  higher  poetry  —  just  because  they  give 
up  the  pretence  of  an  impossible  exactitude  — 
carry  us,  I  cannot  doubt,  nearer  to  the  meaning 
of  the  world  than  the  formulae  of  an  abstract 
metaphysics. 

Such  a  conclusion  may  be  decried  in  turn  as 
agnostic,  but  names  need  frighten  no  one.  The 
agnosticism  which  rests  on  the  idea  of  an  un- 
knowable thing-in-itself  —  the  agnosticism  which 
many  of  Kant's  and  Spencer's  arguments  would 
establish  —  is  certainly  baseless.  But  there  are 
regions  of  speculation  where  agnosticism  is  the 
only  healthy  attitude.  Such  a  region  I  hold  to 
be  that  of  the  Absolute  as  such.  But  because 
the  Absolute  in  this  sense  cannot  be  compassed 
by  the  finite  mind,  it  by  no  means  follows  that 
such  an  all-embracing  experience  is  not  a  reality  ; 
on  the  contrary,  the  denial  of  such  a  possibility 
would  seem  to  be  more  than  presumptuous.  And, 
again,  the  ineffable  transcendence  of  the  Absolute 


THEISM  61 

must  not  be  construed  to  mean  that  our  experi- 
ence is  a  vain  show,  which  throws  no  light  on  the 
real  nature  of  things.  Kightly  agnostic  though 
we  are  regarding  the  nature  of  the  Absolute  as 
such,  no  shadow  of  doubt  need  fall  on  the  truth  of 
our  experience  as  a  true  revelation  of  the  Absolute 
for  us.  Hegel  was  right  in  seeking  the  Absolute 
within  experience,  and  finding  it  too;  for  cer- 
tainly we  can  neither  seek  it  nor  find  it  any- 
where else.  The  truth  about  the  Absolute  which 
we  extract  from  our  experience  is  hardly  likely 
to  be  the  final  truth ;  it  may  be  taken  up  and 
superseded  in  a  wider  or  fuller  truth.  And  in 
this  way  we  might  pass,  in  successive  cycles  of 
finite  existence,  from  sphere  to  sphere  of  experi- 
ence, from  orb  to  orb  of  truth ;  and  even  the 
highest  would  still  remain  a  finite  truth,  and  fall 
infinitely  short  of  the  truth  of  God.  But  such  a 
doctrine  of  relativity  in  no  way  invalidates  the 
truth  of  the  revelation  at  any  given  stage.  The 
fact  that  the  truth  I  reach  is  the  truth  for  me, 
does  not  make  it,  on  that  account,  less  true.  It 
is  true  so  far  as  it  goes,  and  if  my  experience 
can  carry  me  no  further,  I  am  justified  in  treat- 
ing it  as  ultimate  until  it  is  superseded.  Should 
it  ever  be  superseded,  I  shall  then  see  both  how 
it  is  modified  by  being  comprehended  in  a  higher 


62  THEISM 

truth,  and  also  how  it  and  no  other  statement 
of  the  truth  could  have  been  true  at  my  former 
standpoint.  But  before  that  higher  standpoint 
is  reached,  to  seek  to  discredit  our  present  in- 
sight by  the  general  reflection  that  its  truth  is 
partial  and  requires  correction,  is  a  perfectly 
empty  truth,  which,  in  its  bearing  upon  human 
life,  must  almost  certainly  have  the  effect  of  an 
untruth. 

We  do  well,  therefore,  to  take  human  experi- 
ence, not  indeed  as  itself  the  Absolute  bodily,  but 
as  constituting  the  only  accessible  and  authentic 
revelation  of  its  nature  to  us.  And,  in  the  inter- 
pretation of  experience,  our  most  essential  help  is 
to  be  found  in  a  true  theory  of  evolution ;  for  the 
divine  must  be  held  to  be  most  fully  and  ade- 
quately revealed  in  the  highest  aspects  of  our 
experience.  If,  again,  we  are  asked  how  we  dis- 
tinguish between  what  is  higher  and  lower,  it  is 
clear  that  no  formal  or  merely  intellectual  test, 
such  as  "  growing  complexity  of  detail  harmon- 
ized within  a  single  whole,"  will  suffice.  This 
may  be  a  characteristic  of  the  higher  stages,  but 
clearly  the  realization  of  an  abstract  formula  like 
this  possesses  in  itself  no  interest  or  value.  It 
is  the  content  of  any  experience  which  makes  it 
higher  in  any  vital  sense,  and  makes  it  of  decisive 


THEISM  bd 

importance  as  throwing  light  on  the  meaning  of 
experience  as  a  whole.  And  in  any  such  esti- 
mate we  must  ultimately  rest  our  whole  case  on 
an  absolute  judgment  of  value.  Man,  says  Kant, 
is,  in  his  typically  rational  activities,  an  End-in- 
himself.  The  life,  that  is  to  say,  which  is  guided 
by  the  ideals  of  Truth,  Beauty,  and  Goodness, 
and  which  partially  realizes  these,  possesses  an 
absolute  and  indefeasible  worth.  Such  a  judg- 
ment represents  a  conviction  so  deep  that  we  are 
prepared  to  stake  everything  upon  it.  Strictly 
speaking,  such  a  conviction  is  not  the  result  of 
argument,  or  a  deduction  from  any  philosophic 
system.  It  might  rather  be  spoken  of  as  an 
assumption,  the  fundamental  assumption  upon 
which  all  subsequent  philosophizing  must  de- 
pend. Without  this  assumption  of  the  infinite 
value  and  significance  of  human  life,  argument 
about  God  is  simply  waste  of  time.  The  man 
who  does  not  start  from  this  assumption  —  the 
man  who  can  embrace  the  opposite  alternative 
—  is  not  accessible  to  any  argument.  For  him 
the  world  has  no  serious  meaning,  and  he  him- 
self has  no  serious  function  to  discharge  in  it. 
He  has  denied  his  calling,  or,  as  Fichte  puts  it, 
he  has  elected  to  be  a  thing  and  not  a  person.  Of 
such  an  one  it  can  only  be  said,  He  is  joined  to 


64  THEISM 

his  idols,  let  him  alone.  Faith  in  God  can  only 
rest  securely  on  the  basal  certainty  of  duty,  and 
the  view  of  human  destiny  and  the  universal 
purpose  that  springs  therefrom.  This  faith  in 
the  divine  significance  of  life  has  never  perhaps 
been  more  nobly  expressed  than  it  is  by  Words- 
worth in  the  sonnet  with  which  he  closes  his 
sonnet-series  on  the  Eiver  Duddon,  and  I  do  not 
think  that  these  lectures  could  be  concluded  in 
any  more  fitting  words:  — 

"  I  thought  of  Thee,  my  partner  and  my  guide, 
As  being  past  away.  —  Vain  sympathies  ! 
For  backward,  Duddon  !  as  I  cast  my  eyes, 
I  see  what  was,  and  is,  and  will  abide  ; 
Still  glides  the  Stream,  and  shall  forever  glide  ; 
The  Form  remains,  the  Function  never  dies  ; 
While  we,  the  brave,  the  mighty  and  the  wise, 
We  Men,  who  in  our  morn  of  youth  defied 
The  elements,  must  vanish  ;  —  be  it  so  ! 
Enough,  if  something  from  our  hands  has  power 
To  live,  and  act,  and  serve  the  future  hour ; 
And  if,  as  toward  the  silent  tomb  we  go, 
Through  love,  through  hope,  and  faith's  transcendent 

dower, 
We  feel  that  we  are  greater  than  we  know." 


fflsmmmm 


..■;■'■•'■■■':■■ 

M 


m 


m 


■HllslHHi 


^BB 


LIBRARY  OF  CONGRESS    Q 


0  020  199  817  7