BISTOTLE

■ii^HiS PhEDECESSOFSS

THVLOl^

Ex Libris C. K. OGDEN

THE LIBRARY

OF

THE UNIVERSITY

OF CALIFORNIA

LOS ANGELES

ARISTOTLE

ON HIS PREDECESSORS

BEING THE FIRST BOOK OF HIS METAPHYSICS

TRANSLATED FROM THE TEXT EDITION OF W, CHRIST, WITH INTRODUCTION AND NOTES

BT

A. E. TAYLOR, M. A.

FELLOW OF MERTON COLLEGE, OXFORD

FROTHINGHAM PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN MCGILL

UNIVERSITY, MONTREAL

CHICAGO THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING CO.

LONDON AGENTS

Kbgan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., Ltd. iqo7

Copyright, 1907

BY

THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING CO.

H3M

CONTENTS

PAGE

Preface ......••• 3

Introduction :

I. Life of Aristotle I3

II. The Metaphysics i?

III. Historical Value of Aristotle's Criticism . . 29

Summary ......••• 45

Chronological Table of the Pre-Aristotelian Philos- ophers Referred to in Metaphysics A . . 5^ Books of Reference ...... 60

Aristotle on his Predecessors:

Chapter I. The Origin of Knowledge and Wi.sdom

(Philosophy) 67

Chapter II. General Character of Wisdom . . 72

Chapter III. Four Kinds of Causes: A Review of Their

Treatment in the Past ... 78

Chapter IV. Teleology and the Formative Principle 86 Chapter V. Mathematicians, Pythagoreans, and Elea-

tics 91

Chapter VI. The Peculiarities of Plato . . .100

Chapter VII. The Four Conceptions of Cause United

in Aristotle . . . . 105

Chapter VIII. The Defects of the Pre-.\ristotelian Sys- tems ......

Chapter IX. ..^ Criticism of Plato . . . 116

Chapter X. Conclusion ...... 138

Appendix A. On the Cognition of Universal .^.xioms, as a Product of Experience . . . . . '43

.\ppENDix B. The Four Senses of Cause . . . i49

Appendix C. A Popular Resume of the Main Arguments Against the Platonic Ideas, with Special Reference to the

"Idea of Good" 153

Appendix D. The Alleged Difficulty in the Connection of

Mathematics with the Doctrine of Ideas .... 155 Index to Proper N.\mes ...... 160

08

>ino^^^O

PREFACE.

PREFACE.

The present little work makes no ambitious pretence to originality of any kind. Its object is simply to supply students and teachers of philosophy, especially on the Amer- ican continent, with a faithful rendering of Aristotle's critical sketch of the history of Greek speculative thought down to his own time. Having experienced the need of such a work in connection with my own lectures at McGill University, I have thought that others of my colleagues may also be glad that the want should be, in however im- perfect a manner, remedied. This cannot, I think, be done by the reissue of any translation, however meritorious in itself, dating from a period in which our knowledge both of the text of Aristotle and of the early history of Greek thought was more imperfect than is at present the case. Accordingly, I submit to the judgment of my colleagues the accompanying new version, originally made for the purposes of my own lectures, trusting that they also may find it of some service. The translation has been based upon W. Christ's text of the Metaphysics, published in the Teubner series (2nd edition, Leipzig, 1903), and in the very few cases in which I have found it necessary to depart from that text in favor of readings of other critics

7

8 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

the fact has been carefully recorded in a foot-note. I have also, except where the contrary is specified, followed the guidance of Christ in the indication of glosses, which are marked in my translation, as in his text, by square brackets.

The brief notes which I have appended to the transla- lation do not in the least aim at providing anything like an editorial commentary. In general, their object is merely to supply either exact information as to the Greek terms represented by certain words in the translation, or to give references which appear indispensable to the comprehen- sion of the author's meaning. Here and there in the pages which deal with the Platonic theory of Ideas I have, in- deed, allowed myself to transgress these self-imposed limi- tations, and can only plead in excuse the abstract charac- ter of the topics treated of and the unfamiliar form of their presentation.

With regard to the style of the translation, I would only say that, while I have tried to reproduce as nearly as I can the effect upon my own mind of Aristotle's characteristic manner of exposition, and in particular to find some single stock translation for each technical expression of the Peri- patetic system which occurs in our book, I have found it quite impossible to produce, in the rigid sense, a "word- for-word" rendering. I have constantly been obliged, from the exigencies of readable English prose, to vary the Eng- lish equivalents employed for certain Greek phrases and

PREFACE. 9

words of ambiguous signification. I may note in partic- ular that I have preferred "entity," which, in general, in my version represents the Greek <po(7i<; in its widest sense of "determinate object of discourse," also to the more cus- tomary "substance" as a translation of obaia in passages where the term appears to be used broadly as an equivalent for ipoaiq in the sense above explained, without reference to its more special significance in Aristotle's own philoso- phy, viz., that which is a subject of predicates, but not itself a predicate of any further subject. "Entities" I have also employed occasionally, as the most non-committal term I can find, to translate the substantive use of the Greek neuter adjective with the definite article, alziov and ahia^ again, which I commonly render by "cause," I have had once or twice for reasons of language to translate "reason" or "reason why." I have, however, striven to reduce the possibility of misunderstanding by giving, wherever it seemed necessary, the precise Greek original of any am- biguous term in the foot-notes. I ought also to remark that I have, wherever possible, replaced the Greek prefix abro, when used with reference to the Platonic Ideas, by the adjective "Ideal." Readers accustomed to the terminol- ogy of modem exact Logic will perhaps object to my em- ployment of "exists," "existence" as synonyms with "is," "Being," as renderings of iori^ ehat, etc. This has, how- ever, been done deliberately on the ground that the ab- sence of distinction between existential and non-existen-

lo ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

tial propositions is a fundamental characteristic of Aristotel- ian thought.

The works upon which I have most constantly depended in preparing the translation are naturally three: (i) The Greek commentary of Alexander of Aphrodisias on the Metaphysics (latest edition by Hayduck in the collection of Commentaria in Aristotelem Grcsca, published by the Ber- lin Academy). (2) Bonitz's edition of the text of the Metaphysics with Latin Commentary (Bonn, 1848). (3) Bonitz's posthumously published German translation of the Metaphysics (Berlin, i8go). To the last, in particular, I am frequently indebted for the first suggestion of appro- priate renderings.

It only remains to express my obligation to Dr. Paul Cams for his ready response to my suggestion that this volume should be included in the Philosophical Classics of the Religion of Science Library.

Montreal, May, 1906.

INTRODUCTION

INTRODUCTION.

I. LIFE OF ARISTOTLE. In or about 335 B. C. Aristotle of Stagira, a small city of the Chalcidic peninsula, took up his permanent residence in Athens as the head of a philosophical school, being at the time a man of some forty-nine or fifty years. This post he continued to fill imtil a few months before his death, which took place some twelve or thirteen years later (322 B. C). His early history, so far as it is relevant to the understanding of his works, may be told in a few words. He came of a family in which the medical profession was hereditary; his father, Nicomachus, held the post of court physician to Amyntas II., King of Macedonia. It can scarcely be doubted that these early associations with medicine largely account both for Aristotle's wide acquaintance with natural history, as evinced by a whole series of works on zoology, and for the preponderatingly biological cast of thought which is characteristic of his philosophy as a whole. At the age of eighteen he had entered the philosophical seminary of Plato, of which he continued to be a member

13

14 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

until Plato's death, twenty years later (346 B. C). Some- what later (343-336 B. C.) he filled for several years the post of tutor to the Crown Prince Alexander of Macedonia, afterwards Alexander the Great. On the accession of Alexander to the throne the ex-tutor withdrew, as already stated, to Athens and devoted himself to the organiza- tion of his scientific and philosophical school. During the short period of Anti-Macedonian reaction which broke out in Athens upon the death of Alexander (323 B. C), Aris- totle, from his old connection with the Macedonian Court, naturally became an object of attack. A prosecution for "impiety," i. e., disloyalty to the state religion, was set on foot, and, as there was no possible defense to be made, the philosopher anticipated the verdict by a volun- tary exile, in which he died a few months later (322 B. C.).' At the time when Aristotle opened his "school" in the Lyceum,^ or gymnasium attached to the temple of Apollo Lyceus, there were already in existence two such institutions for the prosecution of the higher education, that of Isocra- tes, in which the instruction was mainly of a practical kind,

* The chief ancient authority for the life of Aristotle is the biog- raphy by Diogenes Laertius. There are also one or two shorter anonymous "lives," which are commonly reprinted in complete edi- tions of the "works," and a valuable summary, with dates, by Dionysius of Halicarnassus, the principal parts of which the student will find in R. P. 297.

' From the existence in this institution of a Peripatos, a covered portico for exercise in unfavorable weather, comes the name Peri- patetic as a designation for the Aristotelian School.

INTRODUCTION. 15

designed as a preparation for public political and forensic life, and that of Plato, now presided over by Xenocrates, specially given up to metaphysical, ethical, and mathemat- ical research. To these Aristotle added a third, which speedily distinguished itself by the range and variety of its investigations in what we should now call "positive" science, and especially in the biological, social, and histori- cal sciences. These institutions resembled our "universi- ties" in their permanent organization and the wide scope of their educational program, as well as in the adoption of the formal oral lecture and the "seminar," or informal discussion between master and students, as the principal methods of instruction. The chief differences between the ancient philosophical school and the modern university are, on the other hand, the absence from the former of any pro- vision for the support of the master or "professor" by fees or systematic endowments, and the prolongation of the relation of master and pupil through a much longer period, often until the death of one or the other. The character of the philosophical writings of Aristotle (such as the Metaphysics, Physics, Ethics) makes it clear that they are for the most part not "works" prepared for circulation at all, but the manuscripts of a "professor's" lectures, written out in full for oral delivery, and preserved after his death by disciples whose main object was, not to construct readable and well-arranged books, but to preserve the maximum of the master's words at any cost in repetitions and longueurs.

i6 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

It is only on this supposition that we can reasonably account for the inequalities, abruptness, and frequent irregularity of their style, and the extraordinary amount of repetition which occurs in them.* The actual "literary works" of Aristotle were the dialogues, intended not for study in a philosophical seminary, but for general circulation among the reading public of Athens. These dialogues, which were presumably in the main composed while their author was still a member of the Platonic Academy and before he had entered on his career as the head of an independent institution, were widely celebrated in antiquity for their literary grace, a quality by no means conspicuous in the Aristotelian writings now extant; portions of them have been suspected by modern scholars to have been incor- porated in some of the more elegant and popular parts of the existing writings, and others are occasionally quoted by later authors, but as a whole they have perished. Thus we have to compare the extant books of Aristotle, in respect of their literary character, not so much with those of Plato, or Descartes, or Hume, as with the posthumously published volumes of lectures by which the philosophy of Hegel has chiefly been preserved.

' Cf. the remarks of Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. xi-xviii.

INTRODUCTION. i?

II.

THE METAPHYSICS.

The fourteen books which contain the substance of Aris- totle's lectures on the ultimate conceptions of philosophy are cited by the ancient commentators and designated in the MSS. by the title rd fierd rd ^uffud, whence has arisen our name Metaphysics. The title, however, is one which gives no indication of the nature of the subjects considered, and is never employed by the author himself, rd p-zra xd yuffixd means, literally, simply the (lectures) which come after the (lectures) on "Physics," and indicates only that in the traditional arrangement adopted by ancient students of Aristotle the fourteen books of Metaphysics were made to follow on the eight books of (pucnxd, or "Lectures on Physics." This arrangement may have been adopted either because, as the numerous allusions in the first book of the Metaphysics to previous explanations given in "our discourses on Physics" are enough of themselves to show, Aristotle composed the Metaphysics after the Physics, or because a knowledge of the main doctrines of the latter is presupposed by the former, or for both reasons. (The notion of some of the ancient expositors that the Metaphys- ics are so-called because the objects of which they treat are more sublime and recondite than those of Physics is more far-fetched and probably historically mistaken.)

When we ask what is the character of the subject which

i8 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

Aristotle is expounding in these books, and how the science of "Metaphysics" differs from other sciences in scope and aim, we are thus thrown back from the insignificant title bestowed on the work by ancient tradition to a study of the names actually employed by Aristotle to denote this division of his philosophy. Of such names, we find, on inquiry, he has three. The subject of his present course of lectures is called "Wisdom," "Theology," "first Philosophy." ^ Of the three, the last is the most characteristic and, as we might say, the official designation of the science. Of the other two, "Wisdom" is simply an honorific appellative, indica- tive of Aristotle's conviction that "first Philosophy" is the highest and noblest exercise of the intellect; "Theology," again, is, so far as it goes, a correct designation, since "first Philosophy" is a study of ultimate first principles, and, in the Aristotelian Philosophy, God is such an ultimate princi- ple. But God is only one ultimate principle among others, and thus "Theology," the doctrine of God, is, strictly speak- ing, only one part, though in a sense the culminating part, of the Aristotelian "first Philosophy. "=> What, then, is "first Philosophy," and what are the "second Philosophies" from which Aristotle wishes to discriminate it ? To answer this question we have to turn our attention to Aristotle's classifi-

' For the name "wisdom" {aofia), see chapters i and 2 of the present work, passim. For the other two designations, compare particularly the passage from Metaphysics E, i, quoted below.

'Thus, strictly speaking, the "doctrine of God" only occupies half of one of the fourteen books of our existing Metaphysics, viz. : the second half of book A (c s. 6-10).

INTRODUCTION. i9

cation of the sciences. The deepest and most radical distinction among the forms of knowledge, according to Aristotle, is that between the Theoretical or Speculative (dswprjTixai) and the Practical Sciences, a distinction roughly corresponding to that which we draw in English between the sciences and the arts. Speculative Philosophy (the tout ensemble of the speculative) differs from Practical Philosophy (the tout ensemble of the practical sciences) alike in its purpose, its subject-matter, and its formal logical character. The purpose of "theoretical" Philosophy as its name shows, is Oscopta^ disinterested contemplation or recognition of truths which are what they are independ- endy of our personal volition; its end is to know; the purpose of "practical" Philosophy, on the contrary, is to devise rules for successful interference with the course of events, to produce results which, but for our intervention, would not have come about; its end is thus to do or to make something. Hence arises a corresponding difference in the objects investigated by the two branches of Philos- ophy. Speculative Philosophy is exclusively concerned with what Aristode calls rd fii] ivdexo/xeva aXXux; e^scv, "things which can by no possibility be otherwise," truths and relations independent of human volition for their existence, and calling merely for recognition on our part; "eternal verities," to speak after the fashion of Leibnitz. Practical Philosophy has to do exclusively with relations which human action can modify, things which can be altered in various

20 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

ways; as Aristotle calls them, ra ^>ds^6fi£va akXwq exeiv^ "things which can possibly be otherwise," the "contingent." And hence arises again a logical difference between the conclusions of speculative and those of practical Science. Those of the former are rigidly universal truths which are deducible with logical necessity from self-evident axiomatic principles. Those of the latter, precisely because they relate to "what can possibly be otherwise," what is capable of alteration, are never rigid imiversals; they are general rules which hold good <«? e^^ to noXu, "in the great majority of cases," but which are all liable to occasional exceptions, owing to the unstable and contingent character of the facts with which they deal. It is, according to Aristotle, a con- vincing proof of a philosopher's dnatdsuaia^ "lack of ground- ing in Logic," that he looks to the results of practical sciences (e. g., the detailed precepts of Ethics) for a higher degree of certainty and universality than the contingent nature of their subject-matter permits.^

*Cf. for all this, Eihica Nicomachea vi 2, 1139a 6-31, vi 4, 1140a 1-23

'Cf. e. g. Ethica Nic. I 3, 1094b 19. "Such being the nature of our subject-matter and our axiomatic principles, we must be satis- fied with establishing results which are true roughly and in their general outline, and, since the facts of which we treat and the princi- ples from which we reason are true only in the generality of cases, we must be content with conclusions of the same kind. . . . The man of logical training will only seek such a degree of certainty in each branch of study as the character of the objects studied permits. To demand demonstration from a statesman is an enor of the same kind as to be content with probable reasoning in a mathematician."

INTRODUCTION. 21

"First Philosophy," then, is essentially a "speculative science;" its aim is knowledge, the recognition of eternally valid truths; not action, the production of changes in the contingent world-order around us. It is on this ground especially that in our present book Aristotle, with his char- acteristic preference for the life of the student rather than that of the "man of affairs," claims the honorific title of "wisdom," traditionally consecrated to the worthiest and most exalted form of mental activity, for "first Philosophy." We have next to determine the exact position of "first Philosophy" among the various divisions of "speculative science," and its relation to the sister branches. Plato, in- deed, had taught that all the sciences are, in the end, deductions from a single set of ultimate principles which it is the business of the supreme science of "Dialectic" to discover and formulate.* On such a view there would, of course, be no "sister" branches, no "second Philosophy." Dialectic would, in the last resort, be not only the supreme but the only science, just as a growing school of thinkers maintains to-day that all "exact" or "pure" science is simply Logic. This is, however, not Aristotle's view. According to him, speculative philosophy falls into a num- ber of distinct and independent, though not co-ordinate, branches, each with its own characteristic special subject of investigation, and its own special axiomatic principles. "First Philosophy," though, as we shall see directly, the

* Plato, Republic vi, 5iob-Siid,

22 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

paramount branch of speculative science, is only prima inter pares.

How many distinct branches of speculative science, then, are there? Aristotle answers that there are three, "first" Philosophy, Mathematics, Physics. The logical basis of this classification is explained in the following important passage from Metaphysics E, i, 1026a 10-32: "If there is anything which is eternal and immutable and has an independent and separable existence,' manifestly the cog- nition of it belongs to speculative science, since it is neither the object of Physics (which is a science of things capable of motion) nor of Mathematics, but of a study logically prior to both of them.^ For Physics deals with objects which have no existence separable [from matter, Tr.], but are not devoid of motion, and Mathematics, in some of its branches,' with objects which are incapable of motion and have, perhaps, no separa- ble existence, but are inherent in matter, whereas the objects

of first Philosophy are both separate andfedevoid of motion.

4

•"Independent and separable;" Greek, 'j^wpiarov. The double epithet seems required in English to bring out the full sense.

' The qualification is inserted simply because Aristotle has not yet given the formal proof, that the objects of Geometry and Arithme- tic themselves are not independent entities, but mere predicates of matter, though investigated by the mathematician in abstraction from the matter which, in fact, they qualify. This proof he attempts later in M. 3. At present, he seems to be merely appeahng to the existence of such branches of mathematics as Optics and Harmonics as obvious examples of the distinction in question.

INTRODUCTION. 23

Now, all causes must necessarily be eternal, but most of all these, for they are the causes of the visible divine things.* Thus there will be three speculative philosophies, the mathe- matical, the physical, the theological. For, manifestly, if the divine exists at all, it is to be found in such a class of enti- ties as that just described, and the noblest science must have the noblest class of objects for its study. Thus the speculative sciences are of superior worth to all others, and this study of superior worth to the rest of the speculative sciences. k The question might, indeed, be raised whether first philosophy is of universal scope or confined to the study of a single department and a single class of entities. For even in Mathematics, the different branches are not co-ordinate; Geometry and Astronomy are confined to special classes of entities, but universal Mathematics' embraces all alike. If, then, there are no substances besides those which arise in the course of nature, Physics will be "first" Philosophy. But if there is a substance which is immutable, it will be logically prior, and the Philosophy which studies it will be "first" Philosophy, and because "first" will be universal. And it will be for this science to study Being as such, both as to what its funda-

* i. e., The heavenly bodies.

' i. e., Arithmetic, the principles of which are presupposed by every form of special mathematical study. Cf. below in the present book, C. 2, 982a 26.

24 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

mental character is and as to the attributes which are predicable of it qua Being.*

We see from this explanation both why there are three distinct branches of Speculative Science, and why one of the three has a logical position of priority over the other two, which justifies the name "first" Philosophy. "First" Philosophy, to begin with, is logically prior to the other sciences on the same ground on which Aristotle tells us in the present book that Arithmetic is "prior" to Geometry; its initial assumptions are simpler and less complicated than theirs. Physics is a study of the relations between objects which possess the double qualification of being embodied in concrete material form and being, potentially at least, in motion. In Mathematics one of these restric- tions is removed; we consider objects (points, lines, sur- faces) which are motionless and immutable, and the pre- suppositions of Mathematics are consequently so far simpler than those of Physics. (It was on this ground, it will be remembered, that Plato, in the educational scheme of Book vii. of the Republic, had contended that the study of Arithmetic and Geometry, plane and solid, should precede that of Kinetics or Astronomy.) But the other restriction

•Thus we get the following classification:

Science

\

I I

Speculative Practical

I \ ^1 .

First PhUosophy Mathematics Physics

INTRODUCTION. 25

still remains. The objects of Mathematics, according to Aristotle, are still things which have no existence except as modifications or attributes of concrete material things. They are, in fact, the numerical properties of collections of concrete objects, or again, ideal boundaries and limits of sensible bodies. It is true that the mathematician makes abstraction from this fact, and treats it as though it were not there. He talks of numbers, lines, planes, etc., as though they were things with an independent exist- ence of their own. But the fact, according to Aristotle, is none the less there, and it is the business of a sound Logic of the sciences to call attention to it. Numbers are really always numbers of something, of men, of horses, oxen, etc. "Two and two are four" means "two men (horses) and two men {horses) are four men (fwrses)." Only, as the numerical result is always the same whether you are counting men or horses, there is no need to specify the particular character of the objects you are counting. So with Geometry; a plane is, e. g., always the boimdary of a certain physical solid body, only, for the purposes of Plane Geometry, it may not be neces- sary to take this into consideration.' But in "first" Philosophy this restriction, too, is removed. We study Being not, like the physicist, in so far as it is composed of

I need not say that I am not here giving my adhesion to this view of the nature of mathematical science, but merely epitomising th€ position assumed by Aristotle.

26 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

bodies in motion,* or like the mathematician, in so far as it possesses number and spatial form, but in all its generality; we investigate what it means to be, and what relations between Beings are deducible from the great fundamental condition that they one and all are. This is why "first" Philosophy, as compared with the other speculative sciences, has a higher degree of universality in its scope. The prop- ositions of the physicist become false if they are asserted about anything except bodies in motion ; those of the mathe- matician become false when asserted of subjects which are neither numerable collections nor the spatial forms of bodies. The general principles of "first" Philosophy are applicable alike to God, to a geometrical figure, to a physical corpuscle, since each of these three is something of which you can say that it has being or is. At the same time, there is one class of "things which are" which may be regarded as constituting in a very special sense the object of "first" Philosophy, conversant though that science is, in a way, with everything. This is the class of immutable entities which have neither bodies nor spatial form of any kind, and are therefore excluded from the purview both of Phys- ics and of Mathematics. The chief of such entities is God,

* Strictly speaking, this description unduly narrows the scope of Physics as conceived by Aristotle. With him "matter," the sub- stratum of change, is not necessarily corporeal, and "motion" includes every species of quantitative and qualitative change. Thus, since the human soul is something which grows and develops, Psychology is a branch of Physics.

INTRODUCTION. 27

the immaterial and immutable source of the vital move- ment in the universe, and hence the appropriateness of the name "Theology" or "Science of God" as a synonym for "first Philosophy" itself. Now, Aristotle holds that any complete explanation of any process, e. g., the simplest proc- ess of physical change, involves the introduction of this concept of God as an eternal and immaterial "first mover;" hence, the "doctrine of God" is the necessary crown and culmination of the physical sciences themselves. This explains how, in his conception of "first" Philosophy, the notion of a "Science of God" and that of a most universal science of the "principles of Being as such" come to be so completely fused. The business of "first" Philosophy thus comes to consist in the analysis of the conception of individual Being or Substance {ouaia) as such, i. e., the determination of the fundamental meaning, the ri tazi (or what is it ?) of Being, and the analysis of individual Being into its logical factors or elements. These constituent factors constitute, in Aristotelian language, the Causes or First Principles of Being. Thus it becomes possible to describe the science of "first" Philosophy, as is done in the opening chapter of our present book, as the Science of the Causes and Principles of all Being. Aristotle believed him- self to have finally performed the requisite analysis by his doctrine of the Four Causes (see appendix B and the notes there), and the part which they play in the develop- ment of the individual substance from mere possibility or

28 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

potentiality into actual existence. Accordingly, we find that the central books of our Metaphysics constitute a treatise of which the principal topics are the nature of individual substance, the doctrine of the four Causes, and the conception of the development from potential to actual existence. Outside this general scheme fall the two con- cluding books, M and N, which contain a polemic against the mathematical philosophy of the Pythagoreans and Plato; book K, a patchwork r^sum^, presumably by a later hand, of various portions of the Physics and Metaphysics; book ^, a treatise on the principal equivocal terms of philosophy; book a, a brief introductory account of "first" Philosophy, which was widely recognized, even in antiquity, as non-Aristotelian ; and our present book A , which forms an historical introduction to the whole work, and has the inter- est of being the earliest known systematic attempt at writ- ing the History of Philosophy. As the present work is ofifered merely as a translation of this historical sketch, and not as a specimen of Aristotelian metaphysics, I shall at once proceed to terminate these introductory remarks with a few observations upon Aristotle's method of writing philo- sophical histo^}^

INTRODUCTION. 29

III.

HISTORICAL VALUE OF ARISTOTLE'S CRITICISM.

Perhaps the greatest of the many obligations which hu- man thought owfs to Aristotle and his school is that they were the first thinkers to realize at all adequately the impor- tance of systematic historical research into the evolution of ideas and institutions. To such research x\ristotle would naturally be led both by his natural bias in favor of acquaintance with detailed scientific fact and by his early medical and biological training, which predisposes him to make the development of a finished and articulate product from crude and indeterminate beginnings the central conception of his whole philosophy. Accordingly, we find that the first systematic histories, alike of ideas and of social institutions, are all the work of Aristotle and his immediate pupils. Thus, to take only a few examples constitutional histor}% if we except a few tentative contri- butions from Plato,' begins with the series of sketches of political institutions in various commonwealths, known to the ancients as the Ko^creTa^ oi Aristotle, though they

* See, particularly, the long and interesting passages on the suc- cessive transformations by which "patriarchal" government, accord- ing to Plato, passed into historical monarchy, and on the development of the Persian and Athenian constitutions in Laws, Book III. The better known sketch of the successive degenerations from the ideaj constitution in Republic, Books VIII-IX, stands on a rather different footing, as its object is to establish an order of spiritual affinity rather than one of historical sequence.

30 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

must have been the work not of the master alone but of a whole band of pupils, of which we have an extant specimen in the recently recovered ''Constitution 0} Athens.'' The earliest sketches of the history of Philosophy and Psychology are those contained in the present book and in the first book of the treatise de Anima, respectively. The earliest outline of the history of Physics is similarly that given by Aristotle in the opening chapters of the first book of his "Lectures on Physics." The first separate and complete history of Phys- ics was composed by Aristotle's pupil and immediate suc- cessor, Theophrastus, and the first history of Mathematics by another disciple, Eudemus,^ and it is principally to second or third hand epitomes and to later citations from these works that we are still indebted for our detailed knowledge of the development of early Greek science in both these departments.

To make a discriminating use of Aristotle's sketch of pre- vious philosophical thought we need, however, to bear care- fully in mind both the special object for which it is avowedly designed, and certain mental peculiarities of its author. Our present book, as Aristotle is careful to indicate, is meant

* The dependence of the epitome of physical theories known as the Placita Philosophorum, which has been preserved to us in a double form in the writings ascribed to Plutarch and in the Eclogce of Stobaeus, on the lost 0u<T(xa\ Jo^ai of Theophrastus was estab- lished by Diels in the prolegomena to his Doxographi Graeci; the work of Eudemus is mainly known to us from the use made of it by the Neo- Platonic philosopher, Proclus, in his commentary on the first book of Euclid's Elements.

INTRODUCTION. 31

not as an independent contribution to the history of thought, but strictly as an introduction to Aristotelian "first" Philos- ophy as expounded in the subsequent lectures. Its purpose is not to give a full account of the "systems" of previous thinkers, but to afford presumption that the Aristotelian classification of causes and principles is complete, by show- ing that it provides a place for every sense of "Cause," and every principle of explanation occurring in the works of the pre- Aristotelian philosophers. This anxiety to confirm his / own views by pointing to partial anticipations of them by earlier thinkers, and even by popular unphilosophic opinion, is very characteristic of Aristotle, who was profoundly con- vinced, as he says himself in the Ethics,'^ that "a widely-held conviction must have something in it," and by no means shared Plato's superb disdain for conventional current "opinion" in matters of philosophy. No great philosopher has ever been farther removed than Aristotle from the mental attitude of a recent writer who protests eloquently , against the intrusion into philosophy of ' ' the vulgar prej- \ udices of common sense." *

We have further to remember that Aristotle, like Hegel in later days, was convinced that his own philosophy was the "absolute" philosophy, the final formulation of that answer

' Ethica Nic., ii73ai. "What everybody thinks to be good, that we say is good; he who rejects this ground of belief will not easily produce a more convincing one." Contrast Shelley's characteristic remark that "E.er>'body saying a thing doesn't make it true."

Russell, Principles oj Mathematics, I,, 348.

■^^/

< t

32 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

to the problems of the human intellect which all previous thought had been vainly trying to express. Hence he looks upon all earlier systems, from the point of view of his own doctrine, as imperfect and "stammering "attempts to formu- Jate a thought identical with his own. What he says more than once of Empedocles and Anaxagoras he might equally, from his own point of view, have said of all his predecessors: "If the consequences of their doctrines could have been put |\C(^ r' ' before them, they would have arrived at my own results; but

\\ ' lysV- ' there was no one to point out these consequences to them, and

ft, ^,fyr:^_^^fy^ consequently they failed to make their theories consistent." Unlike Plato, Aristotle shows little of the imaginative sym- pathy which is required of any thinker who attempts to ^""^ give an uncolored version of the thoughts of minds less in- formed and less developed than his own. Hence, if we relied upon the letter of his statements about cruder and older philosophies, we should often be led seriously astray; when we have, however, made allowance, as it is usually easy to do, for this tendency to read his own system into the utter- ances of his predecessors, what he tells us is, in general, of the highest importance, and it is hardly too much to say that the first book of the Metaphysics, thus cautiously interpreted, is by far the most valuable single document for the history of early Greek Philosophy.'

Aristotle's version of the development of previous Greek philosophical thought may be briefly summarised as follows.

' See Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, p. 370, on which these remarks are largely founded.

INTRODUCTION. 33

The earliest thinkers unconsciously adopted the standpoint of a materialistic Monism. They assumed that the only things which exist are the physical bodies perceived by our 'senses, and that the only question which science has to ask about them is, what is the one ultimate form of body of which they are all transformations? (The Milesian school, HeracUtus.) In Aristotelian language, they were interested only in the material cause of bodies, the stuff of which they are made, and they assumed that there is ultimately only one such original stuff and that it is one of the perceptible forms of matter.^ Their later successors (Empedocles, Anaxag- oras, the Atomists) saw that from such a point of view it is more plausible to regard sensible bodies as complexes of many different and equally primary constituents, and thus materialistic Monism gave way to Pluralism on the question of the material cause. At the same time, half unconsciously, they felt the need of asking a second question : What provides the motive impulse by which these constituents have been brought into just these combinations, and no others ? Thus we get a first confused recognition of the existence of efficient causes and their indispensability to complete scientific expla- nation. (Empedocles, Anaxagoras.) As order, arrange- ment, organization are naturally recognized as good, and their opposites as evil, this entails further the notion of a final cause or rational purpose as present in the order of nature, and thus the conception of end or purpose makes its appear-

' The last clause is scarcely applicable to Anaximander, whomV,^ Aristotle ignores as completely as he can throughout this sketch. ^^

34 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

ance, though at first in a form in which the final and efficient causes of the natural order are not properly discriminated. (Empedocles, Anaxagoras.) Meanwhile, attention had been directed in an unsystematic way by the Pythagorean mathematicians to the importance of discovering the law or constitutive formula by which the elementary constituents of each different kind of object are combined. Socrates further developed this interest in formal causes or constitutive formulae by his insistence on the importance for Ethics of accurate definitions of the various virtues. From these initial impulses arose the Ideal Theory of Plato, in which the conception of the formative law or formal cause, as hypostatised into a transcendent noumenon, is made the center of a great philosophical system, to the neglect, as Aris- totle thinks, of the equally important concepts of efficient and final cause. \ Thus the upshot of the whole review of philosophical history is, that all the four senses of causation discriminated in the Physics have received recognition by pre- ceding thinkers, but that they have not yet been defined with sufficient accuracy or distinguished sharply enough from each other. The task thus indicated as essential to the thorough scientific explanation of things is the task that the Aristotelian "first" Philosophy undertakes to accomplish. It is plain that, though Aristotle does not say this in so many words, he regards as the specially important figures among his predecessors Anaxagoras and Plato; Anaxagoras, because by his doctrine of Mind as the formative cause of the world- order he first gave expression, in however inadequate and

INTRODUCTION. 35

unconscious a way, to the teleological interpretation of the universe, and Plato, because he was the first philosopher to put the problem of determining the "forms" or "real essences" of the different kinds of objects in the forefront of philosophical inquiry.

The extent to which lack of sympathetic imagination has vitiated the historical character of Aristotle's sketch of pre- ceding philosophy appears to vary considerably as we con- sider his treatment of the different schools. From the point of view of the most recent investigation, little can be objected against his treatment of the early Ionian Monists, from Tha- les to Heraclitus, except a tendency to employ in stating their views technical terms of his own system, such as ^PXVt "principle," ffTocxeJov, "element," and the like. When allowance has been made for this habit, we readily see that Aristotle's interpretation of these naive Monistic thinkers is in all essentials thoroughly historical. The same is true of his brief but lucid account of the Atomism in which pre- Sophistic physical science culminated, and his still briefer characterisation of the place of Socrates in the development of thought. We can hardly say as much for his treatment, in the present work, of Empedocles and Anaxagoras. The attempt to distinguish in the system of Empedocles between the "four elements" as the material and Love and Strife as the efficient causes of Nature is quite unhistorical,and Aris- totle's own remarks on Empedocles in other writings show that he is fully aware of this. Similarly it is, from the point of view of objective historical fact, a misapprehension to

36 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

censure Anaxagoras for his mechanical conception of the relation between Mind and the " mixture." The teleological significance read by Plato and Aristotle into the notion of Mind as the source of cosmic order was certainly not promi- nent, if present at all, in the actual thought of Anaxagoras. Still, it may possibly be said that Aristotle is avowedly un- dertaking rather to show how far the utterances of the earlier thinkers would permit of logical development into some- thing like his own doctrine than to determine their actual original meaning. This defence has, no doubt, considerable weight, but one may be allowed to question whether it justi- fies the interpretation of Anaxagoras' "mixture" into a quasi-Aristotelian theory of " indeterminate matter," or the criticism of it in the light of the Aristotelian concep- tion of chemical combination.

There remain three schools of thought towards which it seems impossible to deny, when all allowances for a philoso- pher's natviral bias have been made, Aristotle shows him- self unsympathetic and unjust, viz., the Eleatics, the Pythag- oreans, the Platonists. The sources of his lack of sym- pathy are in all three cases fortunately easily discoverable. A biologically-minded philosopher to whom the develop- ment of the individual is the most salient fact of existence can hardly be expected to show much tenderness for thinkers who regard all change as mere illusion, and consequently, as Aristotle observes, leave no room for a science of Physics at all. Hence it is not strange that, though Aristotle elsewhere correctly indicates the important influence of Eleatic dialec-

INTRODUCTION. 37

tic on the development of physical speculation/ his brief and unsympathetic observations in the present book should entirely obscure the fact that the criticism of Parmenides, by annihilating the logical basis of materialistic Monism, was really the most important turning-point in the whole history of pre-sophistic speculation.^ It is unfortunate, also, that his account of the two great thinkers of the Eleatic school, Parmenides and Melissus, has been gravely vitiated in the case of Parmenides by the assumption that the dualistic cosmology of the second part of his poem represents the author's own views,' and in the case of Melissus, by a pedan- tic objection to that great thinker's incidental transgressions of the laws of formal logic*

Sunilarly Aristotle's unsympathetic account of Pythag- oreanism and Platonism is largely explained by the simple consideration that the leading ideas of both those philosophies are essentially mathematical, whereas Aristotle was by train- ing and natural bent a biologist, and of a thoroughly non- 1 mathematical cast of mind. His criticism of the mathe=-^ matical philosophers in books A, M, N of the Metaphysics betrays much the same kind of misunderstanding as we should expect if a thinker of the antecedents of Herbert Spencer were to set himself to demolish the ideas, for instance, of

> DeGeneratione, A8.324b35 S. (R. P. 148 A.) Compare Burnet, op. cU. 354-6.

' See Burnet, op. cit. p. 192. ' Cf. Burnet, op. cit. p. 195 ff. ♦Burnet, o/>. ct/. p. 341-2.

38 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

Weierstrass or Cantor. In the case^Tthe^Xthagoreans, the difficulty of entering sympathetically into their thought was no doubt increased for Aristotle both by the naivete with which their ideas were formulated, and by the absence of really trustworthy sources of information. It is pretty clear that down to the time of Aristotle there was no Pythagorean literature in existence, and in its absence Aristotle would necessarily depend for information upon the verbal state- ments of such associates as the musician, Aristoxenus, whose historical good faith is far from being above suspicion. (It is probably from the oral assertions of such associates who had been personally acquainted with the latest generations of (5 u.,v*.*ifU- *^ y Pythagoreans that Aristotle derived his decidedly improb- Jtu-vs. iCwt (fi ^t)le view that the Platonic doctrine of the "participation"

*\i-J w* yfJ* i***^' of things in Ideas had been anticipated by Pythagoreanism.)' Whether we ascribe the result primarily to defective infor- mation or to mathematical incompetence, one thing at least is certain, viz., that chapters 5 and 8 of our present book are quite inadequate as an account of the thinkers who laid the foundations of scientific arithmetic and geometry, and made a nearer approximation to the true theory of the solar system than any other pre-Copernican men of science. It is quite impossible to do justice to Pythagorean science, or even to understand its true character, unless the wretchedly inadequate discussion of Aristotle is supplemented by some

* See Burnet, op. cit. p. 302 £f, whose opinion as to the spurious- ness of all the so-called fragments of "Philolaus," though not uni- versally accepted by scholars, seems to me more than probable.

INTRODUCTION. 39

historical account in which due prominence is given to the work of the school in Astronomy, Harmony, and pure Mathematics.^ Aristotle, it should be noted, had com- posed a separate monograph on Pythagoreanism which is now lost, but can hardly, from his lack of sympathy with mathematical modes of thought, have possessed any high philosophical value.

The Aristotelian criticism of Platonism has given rise to a host of divergent opinions and a mass of the most tedious of human writings. Every possible view has been taken of it, from that of those who regard it as a crushing refutation of the vagaries of a transcendentalist dreamer of genius to that of those who refuse to believe that Plato can ever have taught anything so crazy as the doctrine Aristotle puts into his mouth. This is not the place to discuss at length topics on which I may have a more suitable opportunity of enlarg- ing in the near future, and I will therefore merely record here one or two conclusions which seem to me to follow from any unbiased consideration of the anti-Platonic polemic of the Metaphysics.

Aristotle, lecturing during the life-time of Xenocrates,

^ For excellent accounts of the school, see Baumker, Das Prob- lem der Materie in der Griechischen Philosophie, pp. 33-46; Milhaud, Philosoplies-Geometres dela Grece, pp. 79-123; M. Cantor, Geschichte der MatJiematik, I., pp. 137-175. It was the non-existence of •mitten Pythagorean literature which gave rise in later ages to the fiction of the "Pythagorean Silence," the imaginary division of the order into an inner and outer circle, and the tale of the drowning of Hippasus in revenge for his publication of the secrets of the school. See Biirnet, op. cit. p. loi ff.

40 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

his fellow-pupil in the Platonic Academy, undoubtedly in- tended to give a bona fide account of the Platonic doctrine^ A mere polemical misrepresentation, where the circum- stances were such as to make exposure inevitable, would have been suicidal. It is also clear that Aristotle intends to present the doctrine in question as that of Plato himself, and not merely of Xenocrates and the contemporary Acad- emy. This is shown by the occurrence of occasional direct references to expressions employed by Plato in his oral teach- ing, as well as by passages in which the views of particular contemporary Platonists are distinguished from those of "the first" author of the doctrine," i. e., Plato. Hence it seems to me indubitable that, although the doctrine of the Ideal Numbers and their derivation from the One and the "Great and Small" is not to be found totidem verbis in the Platonic dialogues, Plato must actually have said substan- tially what Aristotle makes him say on these topics. If a philosopher of the genius of Aristotle, writing after twenty years of personal association with a teacher of whose lectures he had himself been an associate editor, and in circumstances which make intentional misrepresentation incredible, can- not be trusted to give a substantially correct account of what his master said, surely there is an end to all confidence in human testimony. I would further suggest that the doc- trine ascribed to Plato by Aristotle is in the main consistent and intelligible, and can be shown to be a natural develop- ment of positions which are actually taken up in several of the dialogues, notably the Partnenides and Philebus.

INTRODUCTION. 41

Most of the difficulties found in it by scholars have, I believe, been due to their own unfortunate imfamiliarity with the concepts of Mathematics and exact Logic. At the same time, I think it probable that Plato himself fell into occa- sional inconsist^cies in the first formulation of such highly abstract principles, and certain that Aristotle, from lack of mathematical competence, has often failed to understand the meaning of the propositions he attacks. Some cases of such failure I have tried to indicate in my notes to chapter 9 of the present work. I will here terminate these introductory remarks with the two suggestions (i) that the growing in- terest of contemporary philosophers in the logic of the exact sciences promises to put us in a better position for compre- hending the central thought of the Platonic theory than has ever been possible since its first enunciation,* and (2) that it would be an interesting subject for inquiry whether the forcing of all philosophic thought into biological categories by the genius of Aristotle has not fatally retarded the development of correct views on the logic of exact science right down to the present day.

' Particularly valuable as illustrating the light thrown on Plato's philosophy by a study of the mathematical problems in which it originated, is the work of Prof. G. Milhaud, Lss Philosoph^s-Geometres de la Grece, to which I have several times had occasion to refer in the course of this book.

SUMMARY.

SUMMARY.

CHAPTER I.

Intellectual curiosity a fundamental natural instinct, as is shown by the fact that sense-perceptions are normally pleasant in themselves. The successive stages in the de- velopment of rational cognition : sensation, primary memory ^ experience, art or science [i. e., bodies of general truths which involve a theory as to the reason of facts and a sys- tematic classification of them]. General theory, though often less serviceable for immediate practice than experience, holds a higher rank in the series of intellectual activities, because it involves insight into the cause or reason of facts; hence, we regard it as revealing a superior degree of Wisdom. Historically, hiunan intelligence was first employed in pro- viding for the necessities, and then for the comforts, of existence; science arose, in Egypt, from the existence of a priestly caste for whose necessities and comforts adequate provision had already been made, and who therefore were at leisure to employ their intellect upon speculative inquiry into the reasons and causes of things.

45

46 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

CHAPTER II.

What is the general character of that highest form of intellectual activity which is traditionally known as "Wis- dom ? " By universal consent, Wisdom possesses the follow- ing characteristics: (i) universality of range (conversance with the universal presuppositions of all cognition); (2) profundity; (3) ultimate certainty and validity; (4) finality in its explanations; (5) scientific disinterestedness; (6) inde- pendence of immediate practical needs. All these character- istics will be found to belong in a superlative degree to the scientific investigation of the ultimate causes and principles of existence. The original incentive to such investigation is the sense of wonder and perplexity in the presence of facts which we are^unable to explain. The science thus origi- nated, because independent of all practical interests, is the only really liberal science. It also, more than any other form of knowledge, is "divine," for the double reason that it involves the contemplation of divine objects and that it is the only form of cognition worthy of divine intelligences.

CHAPTER III.

Our object, then, is the analysis and classification of the different kinds of cause. In the Physics we have distin- guished four senses of the term: (i) the jormal, (2) the ma- terial, (3) the efficient, (4) the f,nal cause. A review of the past history of philosophical thought will confirm our con-

SUMMARY. 47

fidence in the exhaustiveness of this analysis if we find that every principle of explanation employed by previous thinkers can be classed under one or other of these four heads.

Now, the earliest philosophers asked only: What is the wo/maZ cause of things i. e., what is the primitive and in- destructible body of which all sensible things are perishable transformations ? Thales, whose reasons for his opinion can only be conjectured, said that it is water (a view which perhaps has some support in early poetical tradition); Anaximenes and Diogenes, that it is air; Heraclitus and Hippasus, that it is pre; while Empedocles assumes the existence of four such primitive forms of body; Anaxagoras, of an infinite number. This leads to a second problem. By what agency have the various transformations of the primary body or bodies been produced; what is the efficient cause of the physical world ? The early Monists ignored this prob- lem, with the exception of the Eleatic school, who met it by asserting that change itself is a mere illusion. Parmenides, however, and the later pluralistic Physicists (Empedocles, Anaxagoras) provide some material for its solution by assigning to some elements an active, to others a passive role in the formation of things.

A further question which obviously suggests itself is the problem: What is the explanation of the presence of Order, Beauty, Goodness, and their opposites in the universe - i. e., what is the final cause of existence ? The first explicit recognition of such a final cause is contained in the declara- tion of Anaxagoras that Mind is the source of all cosmic order.

48 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

CHAPTER IV.

Still earlier implicit hints of a teleological explanation of things may be found in those writers who treat sexual Desire as a formative principle. (Hesiod, Parmenides.) Emped- ocles goes a step farther in recognizing Strife as well as Love as a native impulse in the universe, thus half-consciously introducing a double teleological principle, a cause of Good and a contrasted cause of Evil. But neither Anaxagoras nor Empedocles has a really consistent and well thought-out philosophy. Anaxagoras, in the actual working-out of his scheme, treats Mind as a mere mechanical agent, and only falls back upon it when he cannot find a specific physical mechanical cause of a given state of things. In Empedocles Strife is, in fact, just as much a cause of organic combina- tions as Love, and Love as much a source of dissolution as Strife, and though he professes to recognize four equally ultimate "elements," he really assigns a special active func- tion to Fire and treats the other three, in contrast with Fire, as a single passive principle.

The Atomists, again, Leucippus and Democritus, con- sider only the problem of the material cause, which they solve by recognizing a pair of contrasted factors Body, which consists of an infinity of solid atoms, and Void, or Empty Space, as the ingredients of which things are made.

SUMMARY. 49

CHAPTER V.

Meanwhile, the Pythagorean mathematicians were led, by fanciful analogies between the properties of numbers and those of visible things, to the view that physical things are made of numbers and that the constituent elements of nimiber (which are the Even and Odd, or Unlimited and Limit) are the ultimate elements of the universe. In order to carry out this correspondence between numbers and things, they allowed themselves a wide license in the inven- tion of imaginar)' objects. Some of them, following hints unsystematically thrown out by Alcmson of Crotona, con- structed a list of ten contrasted pairs of ' ' opposite " principles. Their doctrine is obscure and confused, but it is clear that they meant to say that the elements of number are the material causes or constituent factors of things.

The Eleatics, who regarded the Universe as a simple Unity, were in consistency debarred from any inquiry into causation, since on their view all change and all processes of origination must be subjective illusions. Parmenides, however, affords some reconciliation of the Monistic doctrine with actual experience, since he seems to hold that though Being is one from the point of view of rational thought, it is many from that of sensation. Hence, in the cosmolog- ical part of his poem he treats not-Being as a causative prin- ciple opposed to and co-ordinate with Being, and thus reverts to a kind of Dualism. The cruder views of Melissus and Xenophanes call for no consideration.

so ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

Thus we see that all these philosophers recognize the ex- istence of a material cause or causes, though they disagree about their number. They also recognize the existence of efficient causality, though some of them postulate a single initial motive impulse, others a pair of contrasted impulses. The Pythagoreans, also, adopted a dualist explanation of things, but they differed from other thinkers in holdmg that number and its elements are not predicates of some sensible reality, but the actual substance or stuff of which things are made. They further tentatively began to give definitions of some things and thus to recognize the principle of the formal cause, though in a crude and superficial way.

CHAPTER VI.

The system of Plato, though in general analogous to that of the Pythagoreans, has some special peculiarities. From early association with Cratylus, the Heraclitean, he derived a fixed conviction that sensible things, being essentially variable and mutable, cannot be defined. Hence, having been led by the example of Socrates to regard universal defi- nition as the fvmdamental problem of science, he inferred that the objects of scientific cognition are a separate class of supra-sensible entities, which he called "Ideas," and that the corresponding classes of sensible things are connected with them by a peculiar relation which he called "participation," but the Pythagoreans "imitation." The nature of this relation was left unexplained. He further held that the objects of Mathematics form a third class of entities, inter-

SUMMARY. 51

mediate between "Ideas" and sensible things. Like the "Ideas," they are immutable; like sensible things, there are many of each kind.

The "Ideas" being the causes of everything else, their constituent elements are ultimately the constituent elements of everything. These elements are two, a material principle, the "Great and Small," and a formal principle, the One. From the union of these two proceed the "Ideal Numbers." Thus he agreed with the Pythagoreans in holding (i) that numbers are the causes of all Being, and (2) that they are independent entities and not mere predicates of anything more ultimate. He differed from them in (i) taking as his material principle or Unlimited a duality of the "Great and Small " and (2) in regarding numbers as entities of a different kind both from sensible things and from mathematical objects.

Thus we see that this theory recognizes two forms of cause, the formal and the material. IncidentaUy, also, he follows the lead of Empedocles in regarding one of these factors, the One, as the cause of Good, the other as the cause of Evil.

CHAPTER VII.

We see, then, that every type of cause recognized in earlier philosophy is provided for in our fourfold classification. The material cause appears in one shape or another in the philosophies of Plato, the Pythagoreans, Empedocles, An- axagoras, the Ionian Monists. The efficient cause has received recognition from Empedocles and Anaxagoras, not

52 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

to mention the poets who have found a cosmic principle in sexual Desire. The riearest approximation to the con- ception of a formal cause or constitutive law is to be found in Platonism, according to which the Ideas constitute the what or essential nature of things, the One that of the Ideas. As for the final cause, it has in a way been recognized by Empedocles, Anaxagoras and Plato, but not in its true char- acter. Thus our historical retrospect affords some pre- sumption that our fourfold classification of causes is com- plete. It remains to point out the main defects of the various systems.

CHAPTER VIII.

Monistic Materialism (the doctrine of the Milesians Heraclitus, etc.) is defective (i) because its explanations are only applicable to corporeal things, whereas there exist also things which are incorporeal; (2) because it renders the fact of phenomenal change inexplicable, from its inability to recognize e^ae«/ causality; (3) because it ignores inquiry into the formal causes or constitutive laws of things; (4) because the Monistic Materialists proceed on no intelligible principle in their selection of the primary body. We may suppose other bodies to be produced from this primary body either by a process of concretion or by one of disintegra- tion; and again, we may hold that on either view, the tem- poral starting-point of the process is identical with its final resvilt, or that it is opposite. Whichever of these alterna- tives be adopted, we can only reasonably regard either the

1

SUMMARY. S3

densest form of matter (earth) or the least dense (fire) as the primary body. The early Monists overlooked this, and selected then: primary body at hap-hazard. The pluralistic materialist, Empedocles, is exposed to some of the same diffi- culties, and there are also special objections to his doctrine, (i) He holds that the "simple bodies" are not reciprocally convertible into each other, whereas we see, in fact, that they do pass into one another. (2) His account of efficient causality is neither correct nor consistent with itself. (3) His general position involves denial of the reality of all qualitative change. As for Anaxagoras. his doctrine of the original intermixture of all things is open, as it stands, to the follow- ing objections: (i) If such a "mixture" ever existed, there must have been a previous period during which its ingre- dients existed unmixed; (2) it is not true in fact that every- thing will "mix" with everything else; (3) what is united by "mixture" is also separable; hence, if qualities belong to things by being "mixed" with them, it should be possible to separate the "mixture" and obtain pure qualities with- out any corresponding substances. Probably, then, his language about the "mixture" was merely an inadequate attempt to formulate the conception of a common material substrate in physical things devoid of all determinate sensible quality. If so, his doctrine amounts to a dualism of Mind and an indeterminate Matter which closely anticipates the Platonic dualism of the One and its Other, the "Great and Small."

The doctrine of the Pythagoreans, though apparently of

54 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

a more abstract character, was also really intended as a cos- mology. They too, like the early physicists just discussed, held that what is consists entirely of perceptible physical bodies, though their principles would really have been more in place in a system of abstract Mathematics than in Physics. They cannot possibly deduce real motion from their purely mathematical principles, nor can they give any account of the physical properties of body. The cosmical causality they ascribe to number is unintelligible if there is only one kind of numbers and these are identical with physical things.

CHAPTER rX.

To the Platonist doctrine of Ideas or "Ideal Numbers" we may object: (i) That it merely duplicates theunsolved prob- lems of the sensible world by postulating a precisely similar "ideal" world as its counterpart. (2) The supposed proofs of the existence of Ideas are all fallacious. Some of them would require the existence of Ideas of artificial objects and of negatives, others that of Ideas of the perishable. The most exact of them lead either to the admission of Ideas of relatives or to the indefinite regress. (3) The argmnents for the theory of Ideas involve assimiptions inconsistent with the Platonic view of the One and the "Great and Small " as the primary elements of Being.

(4) Those arguments are also inconsistent with the theory of the "participation" of things in the Ideas. According to the former, there must be Ideas corresponding to every logical category of general names, whereas it is implied by

SUMMARY. 55

the doctrine of participation" that there can only be Ideas of substances.

(5) The Ideas are useless as principles for the explanation of the sensible world, (a) They do not account for our knowledge of the things, since, by hypothesis, they are outside them, in a world of their own. (b) For the same reason, they do not accoimt for the Being of other things, (c) Nor do they accoimt for the production of other things. "Partici- pation," "archetype," etc., are mere empty metaphors. For who is the artist who constructs things on the model of these archetypes? Further, it will follow that there can be several archetypes of the same thmg, and also that some Ideas are archetypes of other Ideas.

The mere existence of a Platonic Idea is insufficient to cause the existence of a corresponding sensible thing; and, on the other side, some things come into being of which the Platonists do not recognize Ideas.

(6) Special difficulties arise from the view that the Ideas are a class of Numbers, (a) How on such a view are we to understand the assertion that they are causes of sensible things? (b) What relation among Ideas corresponds to the arithmetical relations between nimibers which are com- bined by addition into a sum ? (c) The theory requires us to construct a further class of numbers which are to be the objects of arithmetic, (d) It is difficult to reconcile the assertion that the Ideas are numbers with the other assertion that they are substances.

(7) It is quite impossible to bring the fundamental con-

56 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

cepts of geometry into connection with the Platonic theory of the One and the " Great and Small" as the universal con- stituents of Being. Plato had seen the difficulty, so far as points are concerned, and had consequently refused to recog- nize their existence. But the same line of argiunent which establishes the existence of lines is equally valid for that of points.

(8) In short, the Ideal Theory is the substitution of mere Mathematics for Philosophy, and merely duplicates the problems of the sensible world. It throws light neither on efficient nor on final causation. Even the conception of matter in this philosophy is mathematical rather than physi- cal, and, as to motion, its very existence is inconsistent with he principles of the theory. Not to mention the impossi- bility of finding any place whatever in the Platonic scheme for certain important geometrical entities.

(9) In general, we may say that Plato has fallen into the error of supposing that all objects of cognition are com- posed of the same universal elementary constituents, and that these are discoverable by analysis. But the truth is (a) that analysis into constituent elements is impossible except in the case of substances, and (b) all acquisition of knowledge presupposes previous knowledge as its basis. Hence, the Platonic conception of a single all-comprehensive science of Dialectic which analyses all objects into their elements is chimerical. Even if it were not, one could at least never be sure that the analysis had been carried to completion. Also the Platonic philosopher, who knows the elements of

SUMMARY. 57

everything, ought to be able to know sense-qualities with- out needing to have experienced the corresponding sensa- tions.

CHAPTER X. Thus we see that all our four significations of the term "cause" have emerged in past speculation, and no others. But the real sense and import of the principles employed has been only confusedly and dimly perceived. Even Em- pedocles, e. g., had a dim glimpse into the significance of formal causes or constitutive laws, though he was unable to give distinct expression to his thought.

CHRONOLOGICAL TABLE OF THE PRE-

ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHERS

REFERRED TO IN

METAPHYSICS A.

B.C.

Thales floruit c. 585 (he foretold the solar eclipse

of this year) Anaximander born c. 610 Anaximenes floruit c. 546 Xenophanes " c. 536 ' AUAmU^wiU Pythagoras " c. 532 (is said to have left Samos

' ICtfr/?Lf ^^<^"^ disapproval of the tyr-

ji^^lA* anny of Polycrates) *Tf

Heraclitus " c. 500

Parmenides " c. 470 (accepting the statements of

Plato in his Parmenides) Empedocles " c- 455 Anaxagoras born c. 500 d. c. 428 Melissus defeated an Athenian navy 441 Diogenes of ApoUonia floruit c. 423 (he is satirized in the

Clouds of Aristophanes produced that year) Democritus born c. 460 floruit c. 420 Socrates " c. 470 died 399

Plato " 427 died 347

S8

CHRONOLOGICAL TABLE. 59

Where a floruit is given without any further explanation it is taken from the notices of the Alexandrian chronologists as preserved to us by such writers as Diogenes Laertius and Suidas. A man was conventionally assumed to be forty years old at the date of his "flourishing."

Of philosophers mentioned in the present book but not inserted in the foregoing list Hippo is known to have been a contemporary of Pericles; the physician Alcmaeon was, as Aristotle tells us, "contemporary with the old age of Pythag- oras," i. e., approximately contemporary with Heraclitus. Of Hippasus nothing can be said but that he was a member of the Pythagorean order, and therefore jvmior to Pythagoras. Of Leucippus we can only say that he was a predecessor of Democritus and pretty certainly younger than Melissus. ^

As for the "Pythagoreans" mentioned by Aristotle, in the absence of names, we cannot date them precisely. The Pythagorean "Order" was violently destroyed at a date some- where between 450 and 410, but the survivors continued to exist as a band of scientific students for some time longer. Among its later members were Philolaus of Thebes, a con- temporary of Socrates, and Plato's friend Archytas, the engineer and statesman of Tarentum, probably about a generation later. See on the history of these proceedings Burnet, op. cit. p. 96 fif.

WORKS USEFUL TO THE STUDENT OF ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS.

[I have omitted from the following list both complete edi- tions of Aristotle's works and general histories of Greek Philosophy as a whole.]

Editions of the text of the Metaphysics. Commen- taries, etc.

Aristotelis Metaphysica, edit. W. Christ. Leipzig, Teubner. 2nd edit. 1903.

Aristotelis Metaphysica, recognovit et emendavit Herman- nusBonitz. Bonn, 1848. (Pt. I., Text; Pt. II., Commentary in Latin.) The most important modem edition of the Metaphysics.

Aristoteles, Metaphysik, ubersetzt von Hermann Bonitz. Berlin, 1890. (Posthumously edited from the papers of Bon- itz by E. Wellmann.)

Alexandri Aphrodisiensis in Aristotelis Metaphysica Com- mentaria. Edit. Michael Hayduck, Berlin, 1891. (Vol.1, of the complete collection of Commentaria in Aristotelem GrcBca, published by the Berlin Academy.) Alexander of Aphrodisias in the Troad (floruit c. 200 A. D.) is far the most trustworthy of the ancient expositors of Aristotle, and the commentary on the Metaphysics, in particular, is an in- 60

BOOKS OF REFERENCE. 6i

dispensable aid to the serious student of Aristotle. There is an earlier edition of the work by Bonitz, Berlin, 1847. The commentary on the first five books, with excerpts from the remainder, is also printed among the scholia in the 4th vol- ume of the Berlin Aristotle.

General works on Aristotelian Philosophy (apart from the complete histories of Greek Philosophy).

H. Siebeck. Aristoteles (Frohmann's Klassiker der Phi- losophie. No. VIII). Stuttgart, 1899.

E. Wallace. Outlines of the Philosophy of Aristotle. Cambridge (Eng.) University Press, 3rd edition, 1887. A useful litde digest of the main positions of the Aristotelian system, the most important passages being quoted in the original Greek at the end of each section. The student should, however, be on his guard against the author's unfor- tunate tendency to read Hegelianism into Aristode.

Works on the History of Greek Philosophy down to Aris- totle.

H. Ritter and L. Preller. Historia Philosophies Graca.JU Y"*^****-* 7th edition, Gotha, 1888. [Referred to in the notes to theUf^CiJj 4iJ^l present work as R. P.] An invaluable collection of the chief /?KJ ftf ^j^ f original texts for the study of Greek Philosophy, chronologic- ^ 9; ^K'tik ally arranged.

H. Diels. Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Berlin, 1903. Greek text with German translation. The latest complete

62 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

CftiW*^ ^ ^^ critical text of the remains of the earliest Greek men of ht^ luMJSfi science,

H. Diels. Doxographi Grceci. Berlin, 1879. A care- ful edition of the various ancient "doxographies," or sum- maries of the theories of philosophical schools, which can be shown to have been ultimately derived from the lost ^uaixai 86^ at of Theophrastus. Particularly valuable are the elaborate Prolegomena (in Latin), in which Diels placed the whole subject of the origin and value of the doxographical tradition as to the doctrines of the Pre-Socratics in an entirely new light.

A. Fairbanks. The First Philosophers 0} Greece. Lon- don, 1898. Greek text of the fragments of the Pre-Socratics with translation. ^^ J. Burnet. Early Greek Philosophy. London and Edin- burgh, 1892. The most important of recent English works on the Pre-Socratics, and quite indispensable to the student.

Th, Gomperz. Griechische Denker. Leipzig, 1896. In course of publication. Vols. 1,2, which bring the treatment of the subject down to the death of Plato, have already ap- peared. Vol. I has appeared also in an English translation under the title Greek Thinkers. London, 1901 .

Learned and vivacious, but lacks the sound judgment of the work last mentioned.

P. Tannery. Pour VHistoire de la Science Hellene. Paris, 1887. Studies of the Pre-Socratics.

G. Milhaud. Les Philosophes-Geomhtres de la Grhe: Platon et ses Pridecesseurs. Paris 1900. A particularly

BOOKS OF REFERENCE. 63

valuable study of the Platonic doctrine of Ideas in the light of Greek Mathematics. The concluding chapter contains some acute examination of the anti-Platonic polemic of Aristotle's Metaphysics, Bks. A 9, M-N

E. Zeller, Platonische Studien. Tubingen, 1839. The last of the studies is an examination of Aristotle 's account of Platonism.

C. Baumker. Das Problem der Materie in der Griechischen Philosophie. Munster, 1890. A full and learned history of Greek philosophical theories of the nature of Matter.

The standard history of the whole development of Greek thought down to the final closing of the philosophical schools of Athens by Justinian in 529 A. D. continues to be

E. Zeller. Philosophie der Griechen. Last ccjffiplete edi- C*^ w ««.-r)t e**t y tion, the4th. 5th edition in course of publication. Separate'fcO^ J > *^ < 1%^ translations of various sections into English: Pre-Socratic f**"^ Philosophy, London, 1881; Plato and the Older Academy, London, 1876; Aristotle and the Earlier Peripatetics, Lon- don, 1897.

/

I

ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

FIRST BOOK OF HIS METAPHYSICS

ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

CHAPTER I.

All mankind have an instinctive desire of knowl- 980a 21. edge. This is illustrated by our enjoyment of our sense-perceptions. Even apart from their utility they are enjoyed for their own sake, and above all the others the perceptions of the eye. For we prize sight, speaking roughly, above everything else, not merely as a guide to action, but even when we are not contemplating any action. The reason of this is that of all the senses sight gives us most information and reveals many specific qualities.^ Now, all animals, when they come into the world, are provided by nature with sensation, but in some of them memory does not result from their sensations, while in others 980b 21. it does. Hence the latter are both more intelli- gent and more able to learn than those which

^ diafopa.q\ lit., "specific differences" of the various kinds of things.

67

68 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

are incapable of memory.* Creatures like the bee, and any other similar species which there may be, which cannot hear sounds, are intelli- gent without the power to learn; those which, in addition to memory, possess this sense learn.

Now, all the animals live by the guidance of their presentations^ and memories, but only par- take to a trifling degree of experience, but the human species lives also by the guidance of rules of art and reflective inferences. In man mem- ory gives rise to experience, since repeated mem- ories of the same thing acquire the character of 981a. a single experience. [Experience, in fact, seems to be very similar to science and art.] And science and art in man are a product of experi- ence. For "experience has created art," as Polus correctly remarks, "but inexperience chance."' Art comes into being when many observations of experience give rise to a single universal conviction about a class of similar cases. Thus to be convinced that such and such a treatment was good for Callias when suffering

* i. e., primary memory, retentiveness; not recall. Cf. De Memoria, 451a 15: "Memory is retentiveness of a presentation as an image of a presented object."

' <pavTaaiaiq

' Reference is to Plato, Gorgias 448c, where Polus says: "Experi- ence makes our life to advance by art; want of experience, by hap- hazard."

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 69

from such and such an ailment, and again for Socrates, and similarly in each of many indi- vidual cases, is a result of experience, but the conviction that it was found beneficial to all persons of a specific constitution, whom we have placed together as a definite class, when suffer- ing from a specific ailment e. g., sufferers from catarrh, or bile, or fever is an affair of art. Now, for purposes of practice experience is rec- ognized to be not inferior to art; indeed, we observe that persons of experience are actually more successful than those who possess theory without experience. The reason of this is that experience is acquaintance with individual facts, but art with general rules, and all action and production is concerned with the individual. Thus the physician does not cure tnan, except in an accidental sense, but Callias or Socrates or some other individual person of whom it is an accident to be a man. Hence, if one possesses the theory without the experience, and is ac- quainted with the universal concept, but not with the individual fact contained under it, he will often go wrong in his treatment; for what has to be treated is the individual.

In spite of this, however, we ascribe knowledge and understanding to art rather than to expe- rience, and regard artists as wiser than persons

70 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

of mere experience, thus implying that wisdom is rather to be ascribed to men in all cases in proportion to their knowledge. This is because the former class know the reaso7i^ for the thing; the latter not. Persons of mere experience know the that J but not the why\ the others recognize the why and the reason. Hence, too, in every department master workmen are held in higher esteem and thought to know more and to be 981b. wiser than manual workers, because they know the reasons for what is done,^ while manual work- ers, it is held, are like some inanimate things which produce a result (e. g., fire hums), but produce it without any knowledge of it. Thus we estimate superiority in wisdom not by skill in practice, but by the possession of theory and the comprehension of reasons. In general, too, it is an indication of wisdom to be able to teach others, and on this ground, also, we regard art as more truly knowledge than experience; the artist can teach, the man of mere experience cannot. Again, we hold that none of our sense- perceptions is wisdom, though it is they which give us the most assured knowledge of individual

' or cause (ahta).

' The remainder of the sentence, which is not commented upon by Alexander, and interrupts the logical sequence, is not im- probably a gloss.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 71

facts. Still, they do not tell us the reason why about anything; e. g., they do not tell us why fire is hot, but merely the fact that it is hot. Hence it was natural that in the earliest times the in- ventor of any art which goes beyond the com- mon sense-perceptions of mankind should be universally admired, not merely for any utility to be found in his inventions, but for the wisdom by which he was distinguished from other men. But when a variety of arts had been invented, some of them being concerned with the necessi- ties and others with the social refinements of life, the inventors of the latter were naturally always considered wiser than those of the former because their knowledge was not directed to immediate utility. Hence when everything of these kinds had been already provided, those sciences were discovered which deal neither with the necessities nor with the enjoyments of life, and this took place earliest in regions where men had leisure. This is why the mathematical arts* were first put together in Egypt, for in that country the priestly caste were indulged with leisure.^ (The difference between art and science

' The word "arts" (ri^vai) is here used, as Bonitz notes, like the Latin ars, to embrace both science and art in the narrower sense.

' Contrast the more historical remark of Herodotus, that Egjrptian geometry arose from the necessity of resurveying the land after

72 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

and the other kindred concepts has been ex- plained in our course on Ethics;* the purpose of the present observations is simply to show that it is universally agreed that the object of what is called wisdom is first causes and prin- ciples.) So, as we have already said, the pos- sessor of experience is recognized as wiser than the possessor of any form of sense-perception, the artist as wiser than the mere possessor of •experience, the master craftsman than the man- 982 a. ual worker, the speculative sciences than the productive. Thus it is manifest that wisdom is a form of science which is concerned with some kind of causes and principles.

CHAPTER II.

Since we are in quest of this science, we have to ask what kind of causes and principles are treated of by the science which is wisdom ? Well, the matter will perhaps become clearer if we enumerate the convictions which we currently hold about the wise man. Well, we currently

the periodical inundations of the Nile (Hdt. II., 109) ; and on the nature of tliis geometry, see Cantor, Geschichte der Mathematik, I., 42-73. Bxirnet, Early Greek Philosophy, 17-20.

' Ethica Nicomachea, VI., 1139b i5-ii4ib 23. The sentenceis probably a gloss, as Christ holds.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 73

hold, first, that the wise man, so far as possible, knows everything, but without possessing scientific knowledge of the individual details. Secondly, that he is one who is capable of appre- hending difficult things and matters which it is not easy for man to apprehend; (for sense-per- ception is the common possession of all, and hence easy, and is nothing wise). Again, that in every science he who is more exact and more competent to teach is the wiser man. Also that, among the various sciences, that which is pur- sued for its own sake and with a view to knowl- edge has a better claim to be considered wisdom than that which is pursued for its applications, and the more commanding^ science a better claim than the subsidiary. For the wise man, it is held, has not to be directed by others, but to direct them; it is not for him to take instruc- tions from another, but for those who are less wise to take them from him.

Here, then, is an enumeration of our current convictions about wisdom and the wise. Now, of these marks that of universality of knowl- edge necessarily belongs to him whose knowl- edge has the highest generality, for in a sense he knows all that is subsumed under it. These

* The distinction between "commanding" and subsidiary sciences is taken from Plato, PolUicus, 260b.

74 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

most universal truths are also in general those which it is hardest for men to recognize, since they are most remote from sense-perception. And the most exact of the sciences are those which are most directly concerned with ultimate truths. For the sciences which depend on fewer principles are more exact* than those in which additional assumptions are made; e. g., Arith- metic than Geometry. And, again, that science is more competent to teach which is more con- cerned with speculation on the causes of things, for in every case he who states the causes of a tiling teaches. And knowledge and science jor their own sake are found most of all in the science of that which is in the highest sense the object of knowledge. For he who chooses science for its own sake will give the highest preference to 982 b. the highest science, and this is the science of that which is in the highest sense the object of knowledge. But the highest objecto of knowl- edge are the ultimates and causes. For it is through them and as consequences of them that other truths are apprehended, not they through what is subordinate to them. And the most commanding among the sciences, more truly commanding than the subsidiary sciences, is that

' The distinction of more and less exact sciences is again from ^\ Plato, Phile^s, 56c ff.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 75

which apprehends the end for which each act must be done; this end is, in each individual case, the corresponding good, and universally the highest good in the universe. All these consid- erations indicate that the title in question is ap- propriate to one and the same science. For this science must be one which contemplates ulti- mate principles and causes; for the good or end is itself one type of cause. That it is not a pro- ductive science is clear, even from consideration of the earliest philosophies. For men were first led to study philosophy, as indeed they are to- day, by wonder.^ At first they felt wonder about the more superficial problems; afterward they advanced gradually by perplexing themselves over greater difficulties; e. g., the behavior of the moon, the phenomena of the sun [and stars], and the origination of the universe. Now, he who is perplexed and wonders believes himself to be ignorant. (Hence even the lover of myths is, in a sense, a philosopher, for a myth is a tissue of wonders.) Thus if they took to philosophy to escape ignorance, it is patent that they were pursuing science for the sake of knowledge itself, and not for any utilitarian applications. This

* An allusion to Plato, TheaeUtus, issd: "This emotion of wonder is vcrj' proper to a philosopher; for there is no other starting- point for philosophy."

76 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

is confirmed by the course of the historical devel- opment itself. For nearly all the requisites both of comfort and social refinement had been secured before the quest for this form of enlight- enment began. So it is clear that we do not seek it for the sake of any ulterior application. Just as we call a man free who exists for his own ends, and not for those of another, so it is with this, which is the only liberal^ science; it alone of the sciences exists for its own sake.

Hence there would be justice in regarding the enjoyment of it as superhuman. For human nature is in many respects unfree. So, in the words of Simonides,^ "this meed belongs to God alone; for man, 'tis meet" to seek a science con- formable to his estate. Indeed, if there is any- thing in what the poets say, and Deity is of an envious temper, it would be most natural that 983 a. it should be shown here, and that all the pre- eminently gifted should be unlucky. But Deity cannot by any possibility be envious;^ rather, as the proverb has it, ''Many are the lies of the bards,"

'The conception of "liberal" science again comes from Plato. Cf. Republic, VI., 499a; VII., 5366.

' Another Platonic reminiscence. The lines are from the poem of Simonides on Scopas, quoted in Protagoras, 344c.

'Again an echo of Plato, Phaedrus, 247a: "Envy has noplace in the celestial choir. " Timaeus, 296 : "He (the Creator) was good, and envy is never felt about any thing by any being who is good."

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 77

nor is it right to prize any other knowledge more highly than this. For the divinest of sciences is to be prized most highly; and this is the only science which deserves that name, for two rea- sons. For that science is divine which it would be most fitting for God to possess, and also that science, if there is one, which deals with divine things. And this is the only science which has both these attributes. For it is universally ad- mitted that God is a cause and a first principle;* and, again, God must be thought to possess this science, either alone or in a superlative degree. To be sure, all the sciences are more indispen- sable, but none is nobler.

However, the acquisition of this science must in a sense lead to a condition which is the oppo- site of our original state of search. For, as has been said, all begin by wondering whether some- thing is so,^ just as those who have not yet examined the explanation wonder at automatic

* Hence Aristotle's own name for what his commentators called "metaphysics" is indifferently "first Philosophy" or "Theology." His doctrine of God as the supreme efficient cause is more particulariy contained in book A (12) of the present work.

^ Or, adopting Bonitz's proposal to transfer the words ror-r T^v ahiav (983a 14) and place them after izasiv (a 16), "whether something is so. So men wonder at automatic marionettes, or the solstices, or the incommensurability of the diagonal. It seems, in fact, wonderful to all who have not yet examined the reason that some- thing," etc.

7S ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

marionettes. So men wonder about the solstices or the incommensurability of the diagonal/ It seems, in fact, a wonderful thing to everybody that something should not be measurable by any measure, even the smallest. But this wonder must end in an opposite, and, as the proverb says, a better state, as it does in these cases when knowledge has been gained. A geometer would wonder at nothing so much as he would if the diagonal were to be found commensurable.

We have explained, then, the nature of the science of which we are in quest, and the char- acter of the end at which this inquiry and this whole branch of knowledge should aim.

CHAPTER III.

Since we manifestly must acquire scientific knowledge of ultimate causes (for in an individ- ual case we only claim to know a thing when we believe ourselves to have apprehended its pri-

' i. e., the incommensurability of the diagonal of a square with its side; or, as we should say, the irrationality oi ^ 2. This was the earliest case of irrationality known to the Greeks, and was probably discovered by the Pythagoreans. The other quadratic surds from V 3 to 'x/ 17 were discovered by Plato's friends, Theodorus and Theaetetus {Theaetet., i47d). Aristotle, who had little mathematical capacity, regularly uses "the diagonal" as his one stock illustration of incom-

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 79

mary cause), and since the term "cause" is used in four senses, to signify (i) the essence^ or essen- tial nature^ of things (for the why is reducible in the last instance to the concept of the thing, but the ultimate why is a cause and principle), (2) the material or substrate, (3) the source oj movement, (4) cause in a sense opposed to this last, viz., the purpose or good (for that is the end of all processes of becoming and movement),' though we have already treated this subject at length in our discourses on Physics, we may seek further light from the consideration of our prede- 983 b. cessors in the investigation of Being and the phil- osophical examination of Reality. For they, also, obviously speak of certain principles and causes. Hence it will be of service to our present inquiry to review these principles, as we shall thus either discover some further class of causes, or be con-

mensurability as a non-mathematical philosopher to-day might use TT. His constant recurrence to this example is perhaps explained by the prominence given to it in Plato, Meno, 82-84.

' ovffta.

^To Tt ^v elvac; lit., "What the being of the thing was found to be," i. e., the fundamental characteristics, or connotation as expressed in the definition.

' The scholastic names for the four senses of cause in the order of their enumeration here are thus: (i) catisa formalis, or jorma', (2) causa materialis, or materia; (3) causa efficiens; (4) causa finalis, or finis.

8o ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

firmed in our confidence in the present enumera- tion.

Now, most of the earhest philosophers regarded principles of a material kind as the only princi- ples of all things. That of which all things con- sist, from which they are originally generated, and into which they are finally dissolved, its sub- stance persisting though its attributes change, this, they affirm, is an element and first princi- ple of Being. Hence, too, they hold that noth- ing is ever generated or annihilated, since this primary entity* always persists. Similarly, we do not say of Socrates that he comes into being, in an absolute sense, when he becomes hand- some or cultivated, nor that he is annihilated when he loses these qualifications, because their substrate, viz., Socrates himself, persists. In the same way, they held, nothing else absolutely comes into Ixing or perishes. For there must be one or more entities^ which persist, and out of which all other things are generated. They do not, however, all agree as to the number and character of these principles. Thales, the founder of this type of philosophy, says it is water. Hence,

'^u<r{?; lit., "nature." In the mouths of the early Physicists, of whom Aristotle is here speaking, the word means the supposed pri- mary body or bodies of which all others arc special modifications or transformations. (Burnet, Early Creek Philosophy, pp. 10-12.)

' (fuai^; i. e., primary form of body.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 8i

he also put forward the ^iew that the earth floats on the water. Perhaps he was led to this con- viction by observing that the nutriment of all things is moist, and that even heat is generated from moisture, and lives upon it. (Now, that from which anything is generated is in every case a first principle of it.) He based his con- viction, then, on this, and on the fact that the germs of all things are of a moist nature, while water is the first principle of the nature of moist things.^ There are also some who think that even the men of remote antiquity who first spec- ulated about the gods, long before our own era, held this same view about the primary entity. For they represented Oceanus and Tethys as the progenitors of creation, and the oath of the gods as being by water, or, as they [the poets] call it, Styx. Now, the most ancient of things is most venerable, while the most venerable thing is taken to swear by.^ Whether this opinion

* Aristotle does not prefer to know the reason of Thales for his doctrines, and the biological character of the reasons he conjecturally ascribes to him makes it improbable, as Burnet says (o/>. cit. p. 4^), that they are really those of Thales. Possibly, as Burnet suggests, Aristotle has, in the absence of positive information about the argu- ments of Thales, credited him with arguments actually employed by Hippo of Samos, who revived his doctrine in the fifth century.

' Probably a "chaffing" allusion to Plato, who makes the sug- gestion here referred to in two obviously playful passages: Cratylus, 402b; Theaeietus, i8ib.

82 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

984 a. about the primary entity is really so original and ancient is very possibly uncertain; in any case, Thales is said to have put forward this doctrine about the first cause. (Hippo, indeed, from the poverty of his ideas, can hardly be thought fit to be ranked with such men as these. ^ Anax- imenes and Diogenes, however, regard air as more primitive than water, and as most properly the first principle among the elementary bodies. Hippasus of Metapontium and Heraclitus of Ephesus think it is fire; Empedocles, all four elements, earth being added as a fourth to the previous three. For they always persist and never come into being, except in respect of mul- titude and paucity, according as they are com- bined into a unity or separated out from the unity. ^ But Anaxagoras of Clazomenae, who, though prior to Empedocles in age, was poste- rior^ to him in his achievements, maintains that the number of principles is infinite. For he

* The remark about Hippo breaks the connection, and is prob- ably, as Christ holds, a marginal gloss.

' Cf. Empedocles, 36 (Stein), R. P., 131b: "There is no com- ing into being of any perishable thing, nor any end in ba::efi:i death, but only mingling and separation of what has been mingled."

* "Posterior in achievements" prol^nbly means simply "later in the date of his activity as c. philosopher" (Burnet). Alterative explanations are "philosophically inferior" (Alexander); "more devel- oped in his views" (Zeller).

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 83

alleges that pretty nearly all homceomerous^ things come into being and are destroyed in this sense [just like water and fire], viz., only by combination and dissolution. In an absolute^ sense, they neither come into being nor perish, he thinks, but persist eternally.

According to all this, one might regard the "material" cause, as it is called, as the only kind of cause. But as they progressed further on these lines, the very nature of the problem pointed out the way and necessitated further investigation. For, however true it may be that there is under- lying the production and destruction of anything something out of which it is produced (whether this be one thing or several), why does the process occur, and what is its cause ? For the substrate, surely, is not the agent which effects its own trans- formation. I mean, e. g., that wood and brass are not the causes of their respective transforma-

' "Homceomerous" things is not an expression of Anaxagoras, but a technical term of Aristotle's own biology, denoting the forms of organic matter (bone, flesh, etc.) which can be divided into parts of the same character as themselves. It is here appropriately applied to the iniinity of qualitatively different molecules which Anaxagoras regarded as the primary form of matter. (Burnet, op. at. p. 289.) The words in brackets are probably a gloss.

^ Reading with Zeller dnXwq, "in an absolute sense," for aXXax;, "in any other sense." The reference is to Anaxagoras, Fr. 17., R. P. 119: "Nothing comes into being or perishes, but there are mixture and separation of things that already are."

84 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

tions; the wood is not the agent that makes the bed, nor the brass the agent that makes the statue, but something else is the cause of the transformation. To inquire into this cause is to inquire into the second of our principles, in my own terminology, the source of motion. Now, those who were the very first to attach themselves to these studies, and who maintained that the substratum was one,^ gave themselves no trouble over this point. Still, some^ at least of those who asserted its unity were, so to say, baffied by this problem, and maintained that the one and the universe as a whole^ are immutable, not merely as regards generation and destruction (for that was a primitive belief in which they all concurred), but in every other sense of the term "change;" 984 b. and this view was peculiar to them. So none of those who said that the universe is one single thing had an inkling of the kind of causation we are now considering, except possibly Parmenides, and he only recognized its existence so far as to assume not merely one cause, but, in a sense, two."* To be sure, those who assume a, plurality of

* i. e., the Ionian Monists of the sixth century.

^ Parmenides and his successors of the Eleatic School. ^ Or "body as a whole" (rijy <puaiv oXtjv).

* The reference is to the duaUstic cosmology of the second part of Parmenides' poem, the "Way of Opinion." It is now fairly

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 85

causes are in a better position to say something on the subject; e. g., those who assume as causes heat and cold, or fire and earth, for they treat fire as ha\ing the nature of an agent, ^ but such things as water and earth in the opposite fashion. After these philosophers and such first prin- ciples, since these principles were found inade- quate to account for the production of the uni- verse, men were once more compelled, as I have said, by facts themselves to investigate the prin- ciple which naturally follows next in order. For it is, perhaps, equally improbable that the reason why there are goodness and beauty both in Being and in Becoming should be fire or earth or any- thing else of that kind, and that these philos- ophers should have had such an opinion. Nor, again, would it have been reasonable to ascribe so important a result to accident and chance. So when some one said that it is the presence of Mind which is the cause of all order and arrangement in the universe at large, just as it is in the animal organism, he seemed, by contrast with his predecessors, like a sober man compared

established, however, that this cosmology represents the views not of Parmenides himself, but of a rival school, probably the Pythagorean, whom Parmenides regards as entirely in error. (Burnet, op. cit. p. 195 £f.)

^The reference is apparently to the active role ascribed to Qre in the system of Empedocles. (Burnet, op. cit. p. 244.)

86 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

with idle babblers/ Now, we know for certain that Anaxagoras^ had conceived this idea, but Hermotimus of Clazomenae is alleged to have given still earlier expression to it. Those who framed this conception, then, assumed the cause of Beauty as a principle in things and, at the same time, as being a principle of the kind by which motion is communicated to things.

CHAPTER IV.

One might even fancy that this point was first investigated by Hesiod, or any other of the poets who assumed sexual Love or Desire as a prin- ciple in things Parmenides,^ for instance, who says, in his description of the formation of the universe: "So Love she devised as earliest-born of all the gods." So Hesiod* writes, "First of all things was the Abyss {x°^o^), and next broad-

^ Cf. Plato's account of the effect produced upon Socrates by the famous statement of Anaxagoras about Mind, Phaedo, 97b fif. Aristotle probably intends an allusion to this passage.

' Anaxagoras, Fr. 6; R. P., 123: "All things that were to be, and that were, all things that are not now, and that are now Mind set them all in order."

^ Parmenides, 133; R. P., loia. Aristotle is probably intend- ing an allusion to Plato, Symposium, 1 78b, where both the verse of Parmenides and part of the verses from Hesiod are quoted.

* Hesiod. Theogony, ii6-ii8.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 87

breasted Earth, and Love conspicuous above all the immortal ones," implying that there must be in the world some cause to set things in motion and bring them together. (How the question of priority is to be settled between these authors is a point of which we may be allowed to postpone the consideration.) But, further, since it was patent that there is also present in the universe 935 ^^ the opposite of good, and not only Order and Beauty, but also Disorder and Ugliness, and that the evil and unseemly things are more numer- ous than the good and beautiful, another poet introduced the concepts of Love* and Strife as the respective causes of each class. For if one follows out the statements of Empedocles with attention to his meaning, and not to its lisping expression in words, it will be found that he treats Love as the cause of good things, Strife as the cause of evil. Hence, if one said that in a sense Empedocles designated, and was the first to designate, Good and Evil as principles, the remark would probably be just, since that which is the cause of all good things is the Good itself [and that which is the cause of all evil things is Evil itself].

* <pdla, "affection," "mutual attraction." Empedocles (for whom see Burnet, op. cit. pp. 245-247) uses for the principle of attraction the names of ^piXorr]^ (= Aristotle's <ptXia) and Aphrodite (— Aristotle's epwqj sexual attraction) indifferently.

ARBTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

As I have said, then, the writers just referred to manifestly had formed the conception, to the degree alrea.dy indicated, of two of the senses of Cause which have been distinguished in my discourses on Physics the Matter and the Source of Motion. Their exposition, however, was ob- scure and confused, and might be Hkened to the conduct of untrained recruits in battle. In the general melee such recruits often deal admir- able blows, but they do not deal them with science. Similarly, these philosophers do not seem to un- derstand the significance of their own statements, for it is patent that, speaking generally, they make little or no application of them. Anaxagoras, for instance, uses his " Tvlind " as a mechanical* device for the production of order in Nature, and when he is at a loss to say by what cause some result is necessitated, then he drags in Mind as a last resource, but in all other cases he assigns anything and everything rather than Mind as the cause of what occurs.^ Empedocles, again, though he makes more use of his causes than

^ fiTj'^avrJ . The metaphor is from the machine used in the theatre to hoist up the god who appears to "cut the knot" of an othemase insoluble dramatic tangle. The idiomatic Enghsh rendering would be: "He treats Minu as a sort of fairy godmother."

* An obvious allusicn to the complaint of Socrates in Plato, Phaedo, 98b. ff: 'As I went on to read fiurther, I found that the

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS.

the other, does not make adequate use of them, nor does he succeed in attaining consistency where he does employ them. At least, he frequently treats Love as a separating and Strife as a com- bining agency/ Thus, when the Universe is resolved into its rudiments^ by Strife, fire and each of the other four are combined into one, but when they coalesce again into the One, under the in- fluence of Love, the parts of each are necessarily separated again. Empedocles, then, differed from his predecessors in being the first to introduce this cause in a double form; he assumes, not a single source of motion, but a pair which are op- posed to one another. He was also the first to assert that the number of the so-called material

man made nc use of his 'Mind,' and assigned no real causes for the order in things, but alleged as causes airs, ethers, waters, and a host of other monstrosities."

' For this criticism, cf. Metaphysics, B, loooa 26: "It is true that he assumes a certain principle as the cause of dissolution, viz.. Strife. But one has to suppose that Strife just as truly produces everything except the One." For a full commentar}' on tliis, see Burnet, op. cit. p. 246.

2 ffTtn)rscwv. The word, which primarily means a letter of the alphabet, is taken by Aristotle from Plato, Theaetetus, 20ie ff, where the analysis of a complex into its simple factors is illustrated by the spelling of a syllable. Aristotle's definition of (jror/^elov, which I shall henceforth render "element," is (Aletaphysics, J 3, 1014a 26) "an ultimate factor present in a complex, not further divisible in respect of its kind into factors which differ in kind." The term was, of course, unknown to Empedocles, whose name for his "elementary bodies" is simply " roots of things."

90 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

elements is four. Yet, he does not employ them as four, but as if they were only two, treating fire on the one side by itself, and the elements 985 b. opposed Jo it earth, air, and water on the other, as if they were a single nature. One can dis- cover this from his verses by careful reflection. Such, then, were the nature and number of the principles assumed by Empedocles.

But Leucippus and his follower, Democritus, say that the elements are the Full and the Void, call- ing the one Being and the other Non-being. The full and solid they call Being, the void and rare Non-being. (This, too, is why they say that Non- being is just as real as Being, for the Void is as real as Body.^) These are, they declare, the mate- rial causes of things. And just as those who regard the underl}T[ng nature of things as one derive everything else from the modifications of this substrate, assuming density and rarity as the fundamental distinction between these modi- fications, so Leucippus and Democritus assert that the differences^ are the causes of everything else. Now, of these they say there are three

* The Greek text has "for Body is real as Void." The context shows that we must emend the reading of the MS. into the sense ** given above. The simplest method of doing this is, vdth Zeller, to substitute eXazTov ioTfidXkuv in gS^h 8.

' i. e., the differences between the atoms of which according to this school Being, or Body, is composed.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 91

shape, order, and position. For Being, they say, differs only in contour [^ueixoq)^ arrangement (dtadiyri)^ sUimtion (rpon^). Of these terms, con- tour means shape, arrangement means order {diadtrrj)^ and situation means position/ Thus, e. g., A differs from N in shape, AN from NA in order, Z from N in position. Like the rest of the philosophers, they also indolently neglected the question whence or how motion is communi- cated to things. This, then, is the point to which the investigation of these two kinds of cause seems to have been carried by the earlier thinkers.

CHAPTER V.

At the same time, and even earlier, the so- called Pythagoreans attached themselves to the mathematics and were the first to advance that science^ by their education, in which they were

* Aristotle explains the unfamiliar technical expressions of the Atomists, which are all words belonging to their native Ionic dialect, by Attic equivalents. I fear my attempt to find unfamiliar synonyms for such common technical terms as shape, order, position is not alto- gether happy, but it is the best I can do. Z is said below to differ from N only in position because it is the same figure rotated through a right ^

angle. The paleographical correction of this sentence by B«is yll^r»fif>M does not affect the sense, and I have therefore been content to 'keep **

the traditional text.

'On the nature and extent of the Pythagorean mathematics, see particularly Cantor, Ceschichte der Mathematik, I., pp. 137-160

92 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

led to suppose that the principles of mathematics are the principles of all things. So as numbers are logically first among these principles, and as they fancied they could perceive in numbers many analogues of what is and what comes into being, much more readily than in fire and earth and water (such and such a property of number being justice, such and such another soul or mind, another opportunity, and so on, speaking gener- ally, with all the other individual cases), and since they further observed that the properties and determining ratios of harmonies depend on numbers since, in fact, everything else mani- festly appeared to be modelled in its entire char- acter on numbers, and numbers to be the ulti- 986 a. mate^ things in the whole Universe, they became convinced that the elements of numbers are the elements of everything, and that the whole "Heaven"^ is harmony and number. So, all the

Milhaud, Les Philosophes-Geomhtres dela Grece, bk. i, ch. 2. Note that Aristotle never professes to know anything of the philosophical or scientific views of Pythagoras himself. On the sources of his knowl- edge of the "so-called Pythagoreans," consult Burnet, op. cit. p. 321.

^Tipmroi; literally, "first," as above.

^ ol)pav6(:] literally, "heaven" meant to the early Greek phys- icists the whole collection of bodies comprised within the apparent vault of the sky. We must not translate by "universe," since it was commonly held that much which exists is outside the oopayo-. An equivalent term of later date, probably of Pythagorean origin, is

XOffflO^,

1

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 93

admitted analogies they could show betAveen numbers and harmonies and the properties or parts of the "Heaven" and the whole order of the universe, they collected and accommodated to the facts; if any gaps were left in the analogy, they eagerly caught at some additional notion, so as to introduce connection into their system as a whole. I mean, e. g., that since the number lo is thought to be perfect, and to embrace the whole essential nature of the numerical system, they declare also that the number of revolving heavenly bodies is ten, and as there are only nine' visible, they invent the Antichthon as a tenth. But I have discussed this subject more in detail elsewhere.^ I only enter on it here for the purpose of discovering from these philos- ophers as well as from the others what prin- ciples they assume, and how those principles fit into our previous classification of causes. Well, they, too, manifestly regard number as a prin- ciple, both in the sense that it is the material of things, and in the sense that it constitutes their properties and states. The elements of number are, they think, the Even and the Odd, the former being unlimited, the latter limited. Unity is

1 viz., Earth, Moon, Sun, Mercur}', Venus, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn, circle of Fixed Stars.

^ In a now lost work, " On the Pythagoreans^

94 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

composed of both factors, for, they say, it is both even and odd. Number is derived from unity, and numbers, as I have said, constitute the whole "Heaven."

Other members of the same school say that the principles are ten, which they arrange in a series of corresponding pairs :^

Limit the Unlimited.

Odd Even.

Unity— Multitude.

Right Left.

Male Female.

Rest Motion.

Straight Curved.

Light Darkness.

Good Evil.

Square Oblong.

Alcmaeon of Crotona appears to have followed the same line of thought, and must either have borrowed the doctrine from them or they from

* On the meaning of this numerical cosmology of the Pythag- oreans the student will find most enlightenment in the works of Burnet and Milha'ud, previously referred to, and the section on Pythagorean- ism in Baumker, Das Problem der Materie in der Griechischen Philo So- phie. He should note, also, the fundamental initial error which vitiated all ancient arithmetical theory, viz., the view that i, and not o, is the first of the series of integers. This view is connected partly with the defects of Greek arithmetical notation, partly with an erroneous assimiption, tacitly made by all Greek logicians, as to the "existential import" of predication.

ARISTOTLE >S METAPHYSICS. 95

him, since Alcmaeon was contemporary with the old age of Pythagoras. His views were very similar to theirs. He says, in fact, that most things human form pairs, meaning pairs of op- posites. He does not, however, like the Pythag- oreans, give a precise list of these, but mentions at random any that occur to him, e. g., White- Black, Sweet-Bitter, Good-Bad, Great-Small. Thus in other cases he merely threw out indefinite suggestions, but the Pythagoreans further under- 986 b. took to explain how many and what the oppo- sites are. From both, then, we can learn this much: that the opposites are the principles of things, but only from the latter how many, and what these are. They have not clearly explained in detail how these opposites are to be reduced to our previous classification of causes, but they appear to treat their elements as the material of things; for they say that Being^ is composed and fashioned out of them as inherent constituent factors. The meaning, then, of those ancients who asserted that the elements of the universe are a plurality can be sufficiently perceived from the foregoing exposition. But there are some' who expressed the view that the all is one single entity, though they differed among themselves

^rijv ouffcav. 'viz., the Eleatics.

96 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

both in respect of the merits of their doctrine, and in respect of its logical character. Now, a discussion of their views is not strictly relevant to our present inquiry into causation, for, unlike some of the physicists* who postulate the unity of Being, and yet treat of its derivation from the one substance as its material cause, they main- tain the doctrine in a different sense. Those physicists assume, also of course, the existence of motion, since they treat of the derivation of the All, but this school declares that the All is motion- less. Still, one observation at least is relevant to our present inquiry. Parmenides appears to con- ceive of the One in a formal sense, Melissus in a material. Hence the former calls it limited, the latter unhmited. Xenophanes, who was the first of them to teach the doctrine of unity (for they say that Parmenides had been his disciple), did not make any definite pronouncement, and seems to have formed the notion of neither of these entities, but gazing up at the whole Heaven^ declared that the One is God. As I said, then, for the purposes of the present investigation this school may be disregarded. Two of them we may disregard altogether as a little too naive, ^

^ i. e., the Ionian Monists, from Thales to Heraclitus. ' Or, perhaps, "contemplating the Universe as a whole." '"Naivete" {aypouia) is a technical term with Aristotle,

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 97

viz., Xenophanes and Melissus, but Parmenides appears, perhaps, to speak with greater insight. For, since he claims that Non-being, as contrasted with Being, is nothing, he is forced to hold that Being is one, and that nothing else exists a doc- trine on which we have spoken more fully and clearly in our course on Physics.^ But, as he is obhged to adapt his views to sensible appear- ances, he assumes that things are one from the point of view of reason, but many from that of sensation, and thus reintroduces a duality of principles and causes, the Hot and Cold, by which he means, e. g., fire and earth. Of these he co-ordinates the Hot with Being, its counter- 987 a. part with Non-being.

Now, from the account we have just given, and by a comparison of the thinkers who have previously concerned themselves with the sub- ject, we have arrived at the following result. From the earliest philosophers we have learned of a bodily principle (for water, fire, and the

for want of acquaintance with formal logic. On the particular logical fallacy to which he objected in Melissus, see Burnet, op. cit. p. 341, and on his misapprehension of the second part of the poem of Parmenides, p. 195 of the same work. Plato, it should be said, held the same view as to the relative merits of these two philosojihcrs.y See Theaetetus, 1836.

' Physics, I., 3, 186a 3, ff.

98 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

like, are bodies), which some of them* regard as a single principle, others^ as a plurality, though both schools treat these principles as bodily. From others we have learned, in addition to this principle, of a source of motion, and this also is regarded by some^ of them as one, but by others * as twofold. They all, down to the Italian^ school and exclusive of them, treated the sub- ject in a rather ordinary^ way. As I have said, they only employed two kinds of cause, and the second of these, the source of motion, some of them regarded as one, others as two. The Pythag- oreans likewise maintained a duality of princi- ples, but they added, and this is peculiar to them, the notion that the limited, the unlimited, the one are not predicates of some other entity, such as fire, or earth, or something else of that kind, but that the Unlimited and the One themselves are the substance of the things of which they are predi-

' The Milesians, Heraclitus, Diogenes.

^ Empedocles, Anaxagoras, the Atomists.

^ i. e., Anaxagoras.

* i. e., Empedocles.

' i. e., the Pythagoreans of Magna Graecia.

^ [itrpicoTtpov. If the text is correct, this must mean "un- satisfactorily," though the word will hardly bear that sense. There is a rival MS. reading /xaAazcurejOov, " rather feebly, " and Alexander of Aphrodisias appears to be explaining a reading fiova^^torepov, "rather one-sidedly."

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 99

cated. This is why, according to them, num- ber is the substance of everything.

This was the doctrine they proclaimed on these points. They also began to discuss the what of things, and to give definitions of it, but their method of procedure was extraordinarily crude. Their definitions were superficial, and they regarded anything to which a term under examination first appHed as the essential nature of the object in question, as if one were to think that "double of" and "the number 2" are the same thing, on the ground that 2 is the first number which is double of another. But, methinks, it is not the same thing to be double of something as it is to be the number 2. If it were, then one thing would be many\ a consequence which actually followed in their system.^ So much, then, is what may be learned from the earlier thinkers and their successors.

* For, if every number which is double of another is the number 2 the single number 2 must be identical with an infinity of other even numbers, 4, 6, 8. . . .

* The, way in which this occurred was that the same number was identified, on the strength of diflerent fanciful analogies, with a variety of different objects. Thus i was "the point," but it was also "the soul."

loo ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

CHAPTER VI.

The said philosophies were succeeded by the system of Plato, which was for the most part in harmony with them, but had also some dis- tinctive peculiarities by which it was discrimi- nated from the philosophy of the Itahans\ In his youth Plato had been familiar with Cratylus and with the Herachtean doctrines, according to which all things perceived by the senses are in incessant flux, and there is no such thing as scientific knowledge of them, and to this part of the doctrine he remained true through life. 987 b. Socrates, however, though confining his exami- nation to questions of moral conduct, and giving no study to the nature of the universe as a whole, sought within the moral sphere for the universal, and was the first to concentrate his attention on definitions. Hence Plato, who succeeded him, con- ceived for the reason immediately to be mentioned that the objects thus defined cannot be any sensible things, but are of some different kind, since it is impossible that there should be a general defini- tion of a sensible thing, as such things are in- cessantly changing. Hence he called this kind of things "Ideas," and held that all sensible

M. e., the Pythagoreans.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS.

things exist by the side of them and are named after them; for the muUiplicity of things called by the same names as the Ideas exist, he holds, in consequence of their "participation" in them*

In this theory of participation the only inno- vation lay in the name, for the Pythagoreans say that things exist by "imitation" of the numbers, and Plato by "participation" [a mere change of a word]. But what this "participation in" or "imitation of" the Ideas may be, they left for their successors to inquire.

Further, he teaches that the objects of mathe-

^ Cf. the fuller parallel passage, Metaphysics, M, 1078a 9 ff: "The theory of Ideas arose in the minds of its originators from their persuasion of the truth of the HeracUtean doctrine, that all sensible things are always in flux. Hence, they inferred, if there is to be scien- tific knowledge and rational comprehension of amiihing, there must be other entities distinct from those of sense, and they must be per- manent. Now, Socrates confined his studies to the moral virtues, and was the first to attempt universal definition in connection with them Among the physicists, Democritus had indeed just touched the fringe of the problem, and had given a sort of definition of heat and cold, and the Pythagoreans even earHer had discussed the definition of a few concepts, connecting them with their theor}' of numbers. They asked, e. g., what is opportunity, or justice, or marriage ? But Socrates had a good reason for inquiring into the what of things. He was attempt- ing to construct syllogisms, and the 'what is it' is the starting-point of the syllogism. . . . There are, in fact, two things which must in justice be assigned to Socrates, inductive argvmients and universal definition. For both of these have to do with the foundation of science, Socrates, however, did not regard his universals, or definitions, as sepa- rable from things; his successors made the separation, and called this class of objects 'Ideas.' "

I02 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

matics exist as an intermediate class beside the Ideas and sensible things. They differ from sensible things in being eternal and immutable, and from the Ideas in this, that there is a multi- plicity of similar mathematical objects, but each Idea is a single, self-subsisting entity.^

And since the Ideas are the causes of every- thing else, he thought that their constituent ele- ments are the elements of everything. Their material principle, then, is the "Great and Small," but their formal principle the One. For the numbers [which are the Ideas] ^ are derived from the former principle by participa- tion in the One. In regarding the One as a substance, and not as a predicate of some other entity, his doctrine resembles Pythagoreanism, and also in holding that the numbers are the causes of Being in ever5Athing else. But it is

' From the polemic against Plato, which occupies books M and N oi the Metaphysics, particularly from M 2, 1076b, it appears that Aristotle understood Plato to distinguish between three kinds of entity, each of which is in its ultimate constitution a number, or ratio of numbers: (i) The sensible object, e. g., a visible round disc; (2) the

"mathematical object," e. g, mm Tnmi«J.i«rinn^'nnHr.n-r.f Q par-fof-fly

0. \^i4tL» vrw« uiituUr^sc; (3) the Idea, e.°g., tlie circle in the sense in which it is

^^^ ^j 1^ studied by the analytical geometer, and defined by its equation. (2) differs from (3) as "circles" from "the circle."

>0 O

' The text is ra eldr) too? dpid/iou'^, where either rd s^Stj or Toh^ dpid[iobq is pretty clearly a gloss. I follow Zeller's reading. L»illx ^*W* ^f^ Christ has rd e'ld-^ \ruoq dpcfffiooq], "the Ideas [which are the numbers]. "

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 103

peculiar to him to set up a duality instead of the single Unlimited, and to make the Unlimited consist of the Great and Small.* It is a pecu- liarity, also, that he regards the Numbers as dis- tinct from sensible things, whereas the Pythag- oreans say that things themselves are number, and do not assert the existence of an intermediate class of mathematical objects. This treatment of the One and the Numbers as distinct from things, in which he differed from the Pythago- reans, and also the introduction of the ''Ideas," were due to his logicaP studies (for his prede- cessors knew nothing of Dialectic); his concep- tion of the second principle as a DuaHty, to the ease with which numbers other than primes can be generated from such a Duality as a matrix.^ 988 a.

^ This "Great and Small," or principle of indefinite, variability, is regularly spoken of by Aristotle in the sequel as "the indeterminate Dyad" or "Duality." It corresponds exactly to the notion of "the variable" in modern Logic and Mathematics. The nearest equivalent phrase in the wTitings of Plato himself occurs at Philehiis, 246, where the amtpov or indeterminate is characterized as "all things which appear to us to exist in a greater and a less degree, and admit the quali- fications 'intensely,' 'gently,' 'e.xcessively' and the like." Ac- cording to the ancient commentators, the foregoing account of the composition of the Ideas, which is not to be found explicitly in any of the Platonic writings, was given orally by Plato in lectures which were posthumously edited by Aristotle and others of his disciples.

^ TTji' iv To'is loyoii axi(piv, "his inquiries in the domain of concepts," i. e., his study of the nature of logical definition and divi- sion.

^ A matrix, IxfiayeXov^ properly, a mass of material pre-

I04 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

Yet, the actual process is the reverse of this, and his suggested derivation has no logical foun- dation. According to his followers, the existence of a multipHcity of things is a consequence of matter, whereas each Form is only productive once for all. Yet, it is notorious that only one table^ can be fashioned from one and the same piece of timber, whereas he who impresses the form on it, though but a single workman, can make many tables. So with the relation of the

pared to receive a mould or stamp, a Platonic term borrowed by Aristotle from Theaetetus, 191c; Timaeus, 50c. The clause "other than primes" is difficult to interpret, and has been treated as a mistaken gloss. I think, however, that it alludes to Parmenid-es, 143-4. where Plato deduces from the existence of i, that of 2, and from these two that of the whole series of all the other integers which can be resolved into factors, whether odd or even; i. e., all except the primes. If this explanation is correct, and it appears to have been held by Bonitz (see his edition of the Metaphysics, Commentary, p. 94-5), this is one of several passages which refute the current assertion that the dialogue Parmenides is never cited by Aristotle. Another is N, 1091a 11, which unmis- takably refers to the same passage of the Parmenides. It should, however, be obser\'ed that the two factors from which nxmibers are derived in that dialogue are not the number i and the Variable or "Indeterminate Duality," but the number i, and the number 2, "the Ideal Duahty." This conscious or unconscious perversion of Plato's theorj' of numbers recurs throughout the whole of the sustained polemic of Books M, N.

* The illustration of the table is an echo of Republic, X., 596a. Aristotle is punning on the Literal meaning of the word vkfj^ timber, which he employs as a technical term for the "material" from which a thing is produced.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 105

male to the female; the latter is impregnated by a single coition, but one male can impregnate many females. And yet these relations are "copies" of those principles!

This, then, is the account which Plato gave of the questions we are now investigating. From our statement it is clear that he only employed two kinds of cause, the principle of the what and the material cause. (The Ideas, in fact, are the cause of the what in everything else, and the One in the Ideas themselves.) He also tells us what is the material substratum of which the Ideas are predicated in the case of sensible things, the One in the case of the Ideas, viz., that it is the duaUty of the "Great and Small." He further identified these two elements with the causes of good and evil, respectively, a line of research which, as we have said, had already been followed by some of his philosophical prede- cessors, e. g., Empedocles and Anaxagoras.

CHAPTER VII.

We have now summarily and in outline an- swered the questions, what thinkers have treated of principles and of reality, and what doctrines they have taught. This much, however, can be

io6 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

gathered from our sketch of them, viz., that of all who have discussed principles and causes none has spoken of any kind except those which have been distinguished in our discourses on Physics. They are all unmistakably, though ob- scurely, trying to formulate these. Some of them understand their principle in the sense of a ma- terial cause, whether this be regarded as one or as several, as a body or as something incorpo- real. E. g., Plato, with his Great and Small; the ItaHans, with their Unlimited; Empedocles, with his fire, earth, water, and air; Anaxagoras, with the infinity of his homoeomerous bodies. All these, then, have formed the concept of cause in this sense, as likewise all those who make a first principle of air,^ or fire,^ or water, ^ or a body denser than fire but finer than air;* for, in fact, some have identified the prime element with such a body. These thinkers, then, apprehended only this form of cause; others had apprehended cause, also, in the sense of the source of motion, e. g., those who make a principle of Love and Strife,

' Anaximenes, Diogenes.

^ Heraclitus.

^Thales (Hippo).

* On the identification of the philosopher thus designated, see Burnet, op. cit. 56-58, and references given there. I hold with Burnet that the criticism of the doctrine in De Coelo, 303b 12, proves that the allusion is to Anaximander.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 107

or Mind, or sexual Love. The what ' or essential nature^ has not been exphcitly assigned by any of them, but the authors of the theory of Ideas have come nearest to recognizing it. For they 988 b. neither conceive the Ideas as the material of sen- sible things and the One as that of the Ideas, nor do they regard them as providing the source of motion (indeed, they say that they are rather causes of motionlessness and rest), but the what * is supplied to everything else by the Ideas, and to the Ideas by the One. The end jor the sake of which actions, changes, and movements take place they do, in a sense, introduce as a cause, but not in this form, nor in one corresponding to its real character. For those who speak of Mind or Love assume these causes, indeed, as something good, but not in the sense that anything is or comes to be for the sake oj them, but only in the sense that motions are initiated by them. Similarly, those^ who assert that Being, or the One, are entities of this kind^ assert, indeed, that they are a cause of existence, but not that anything is or comes to be for the sake of them. Consequently they, in a sense, both 'assert and deny that the Good is a

' TO rt ^v elvat.

^Tijv ovffiav.

' i. e., Plato and his followers.

* i. e., Sources of motion.

io8 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

cause, for they treat it as such, not absolutely but per accidens} They all thus appear to supply evi- dence that our own determination of the number and kind of the senses of cause is correct, since they have all failed to conceive of any further sense of cause. Further, it is clear that we must investi- gate these principles either as they stand in their entirety or a selection of them. We will next, how- ever, examine possible difficulties in the doctrines of the individual thinkers, and their views about principles.

CHAPTER VIII.

It is clear, then, that all who regard the universe as one and assume a single entity as its material, and that a bodily and extended^ entity, have fallen into error in several respects. They only assume constituent elements for bodies, but not for in- corporeal entities, though incorporeal entities also really exist, and though they attempt to provide

* i. e., they treat "the Good" as being a cause only in a relative and derivative sense, because it happens also to be something which mechanically initiates movemait.

^ fiiyedoq k'^ouaav; ht., "having magnitude." iiiysdoq (see Bonitz's Index Arislotelicus sub. voc.) means to Aristotle res extensa, spatial magnitude, whether purely geometrical or physical.

I

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 109

causes for generation and dissolution, and to dis- cuss the nature of all things, they do away with the cause of motion. A further fault is that they do not assume the essential nature,^ or what, as a cause of anything. Another is the levity with which they call any one of the simple bodies except earth a principle, without reflection on the process of their reciprocal generation from each other. [I am speaking of fire, water, earth, and air.] Some of them are generated from one another by composition, others by separation, and this difference is of the highest importance in deciding the question of priority and posteriority. From one point of view, one might hold that the most elementary of things is that out of which they are all ultimately generated by composition, and such would be the body which is finest in texture and has the minutest parts. Hence those who 989 a. assume fire as their principle would be most fully in accord with this line of thought, and even each of the others admits that the element of bodies must be of this kind ; at least, none of the later thinkers who asserted a single principle has ven- tured to say that this element is earth the reason clearly being the great size of its parts though each of the three other elements has found an advocate. For some identify the primary element

' TTjv obaiav.

no ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

with fire, others with water, others with air. And yet why do they not say the same thing about earth, too, just as the mass of mankind do ? And Hesiod,^ too, says that earth was the first of bodies, so primitive and popular is this belief found to be.

According to this line of thought, then, whether a man says that the primary body is any one of these other than fire or assumes that it is denser than air but finer than water, he cannot be right in either case. But if what is sequent in the order of production is logically anterior,^ then, since the compacted and composite comes later in the order of production, we should have an opposite con- clusion to the above: water would be prior to air; earth, to water.

So much, then, may be said about those who postulate a single cause of this kind. The same criticisms are pertinent, even if one assumes a plurality of them, like Empedocles, who says that the material of things is four bodies. The same consequences must follow in his system, as well

* In the passage previously referred to, Theogony, 1 16 ff.

"^TTj ^ixTSi Ttporepov^ "prior in the order of nature" it being a doctrine of Aristotle, ultimately based upon his biological studies, that the completed result of a process of development is presupposed by, and therefore logically, and in the end temporally also, prior to its incomplete stages. For the different senses of priority and posteri- ority, see Metaphysics, A 1 1 .

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. in

as others peculiar to it. For we see these bodies produced from one another, and this impHes that fire and earth do not always remain the same body, a point which has been discussed in our discourses on Physics'. And, further, he cannot be thought to have spoken with entire correctness or consist- ency on the question whether the cause of motion is to be assumed to be single or double. And uni- versally those who teach this doctrine are forced to deny the reality of qualitative alteration. Nothing will become cold after being hot, or hot after being cold. For there would need to be something to be the subject of these contrasted states. And thus there would be a numerically single entity which becomes successively fire and water; but this he denies.

As for Anaxagoras, he would be most rationally interpreted if we understood him to recognize two elements. He did not, indeed, develop this notion himself, but would necessarily have followed an- other's guidance in this direction. That all things were at first a mixture^ is indeed a paradoxical

* Reference is to De CceIo, III., 7; De Generatione, II., 6.

^The reference is to Anaxagoras. Fr. (i) "All things were to- gether, infinite both in number and smallness," etc.; Fr. (4) "Before the separating off, when all things were together, there was not even any colour perceptible, for the commingling of all things forbade it," etc.; R. P., 120: "But Mind is . . . not mingled with anything;" Fr. (6), R.P., 123.

112 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

view on various grounds, particularly because it follows that they would first have to exist in an 989 b. unmixed state, and also because it is not the nature of anything and everything to admit of mixture with everjthing else. Besides, the attributes and accidents of things would be separable from their substances (since things which can mix can also be separated). Still, if one followed up his doctrine and developed his meaning, he would perhaps be found to be asserting a view more akin to that of later thinkers. For when nothing had been sepa- rated off, clearly nothing could be truly predicated of the supposed substance. I mean, e. g., that it could not be truly called white, black, buff [nor of any other color], but must necessarily have been colorless, since otherwise it would have had one or the other of these tints. Similarly, for the same reason it could have no taste, nor any other such quality. It could neither have been a quality, nor a quantity, nor a thing. If it had been, it would have had the form of some definite particular thing. But this is impossible, on the assumption that all things were mixed together, for it would be equivalent to being already separated out. But he says that all things were mixed together except Mind, which alone was unmixed and pure. It follows, then, from all this that his theory amounts to assigning as his principles the One (for that

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 113

is simple and unmixed), and the Other, as we' call the Indeterminate before it has been rendered determinate and received a form. Thus what he says is neither correct nor clear; still, what he means is something similar to later theories and more conformable to apparent facts.

These thinkers, however, confine themselves exclusively to the study of generation, dissolution, and motion, for in general they inquire exclusively about the causes and principles of that kind of Being. As for those who study all forms of Being, and distinguish between sensible and non-sensible objects, they clearly devote their attention to both classes. Hence, in their case, we may dwell at rather greater length on the question what satis- factory or unsatisfactory contributions they have made to the solution of the problems at present before us.

The so-called Pythagoreans, then, employ less obvious principles and elements than the physi- cists (the reason being that they did not derive them from sensible things; for mathematical objects, with the exception of those with which astronomy is concerned, are devoid of motion).

* "We" i. e., the school of Plato. Throughout the present discussion Aristotle affects to speak as a critic of Plato from wathin the Platonic circle, a point of which we shall see further illustration in ch.IX.

114 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

Still, all their discussions and investigations are concerned with physical Nature. For they de- 990 a. scribe the formation of the "Heaven, " and observe what befalls its parts [attributes and activities], and use up their causes and principles upon this task, which implies that they agree with the other physicists, that what is is just so much as is per- ceptible by our senses and comprised by the so-called "Heaven." Yet, as I have said, the causes and principles they assign are adequate for the ascent to the higher classes of entities,^ and, in- deed, more appropriate to these than to the science of Physics. But they fail to explain how there can be motion if all that we presuppose in our premises is merely Limit, the Unlimited, the Odd and the Even, or how without Motion and Change there can be Generation, and Dissolution, or the actions of the bodies that traverse the "Heaven." ^ Again, even if it were granted them or proved that magnitude'^ is composed of these factors, how does this account for the existence of bodies, light

'"higher" i.e., reqmring a greater degree of generalising abstraction for their comprehension; in Aristotle's favorite phrase, "farther removed from sense."

^i. e., Res extensa, Body, conceived in a purely geometrical fashion and denuded of all physical properties. Aristotle's point is, that just because the Pythagoreans (like Descartes after them) con- ceived of Body in purely geometrical terms they could give no expla- nation of its sensible physical properties.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 115

and heavy? For they reason from the principles they assume just as much about sensible as about mathematical bodies. Hence they have not taught us anything about fire or earth or other such bodies, and naturally not, as they had no special doctrine about sensible objects as such. Again, how can we understand the view that Number and its properties are the causes of all that is and that comes to be in the "Heaven," both at the beginning and now, and yet that there is no other kind of number than this Number of which the universe is composed? For when, according to them, there is in this region of the universe Opinion and Opportunity, and a little higher or lower Injustice and Separation or Mix- ture, and when they say as a proof of this that each of these is a number, and when it also comes about that there is already in this region a col- lection of composite^ magnitudes, because these properties are attached each to a particular region is it the same number as that in the "Heaven," which we are to suppose to be each of these things, or some other kind of number ?^ Plato, to be sure,

M. e., extended figures or bodies (the Pythagoreans did not dis- tinguish the two), which, according to them, are "composed" of the numerical factors. Limit, the Unlimited.

^ In this difficult sentence I have followed the reading and interpre- tation of Burnet, op. cit. p. 316, which differs from that of Christ in the following points: 990a 25, omit fxiv and, with Bonitz, read aufi/iatvjj

ii6 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

says it is a different kind, though he, too, thinks that both these things^ and their causes are num- bers, but beheves that the causative numbers are perceived by thought, the other kind by sense.

CHAPTER IX.

For the present, then, we may dismiss the sub- ject of the Pythagoreans; the foregoing brief mention of them will be found adequate. As for 990 b. those who assume the Ideas as causes, in the first

for (To/ji/Saj'i'ef; line 28, omit ouroi;-, with the MS Ab), though this last change is perhaps unnecessary. The general meaning is, then, as follows: Besides their cosmological significance the Pythagorean "nimibers," had, as we have seen, fanciful symbolic interpretations, and apparently it was held that the various immaterial entities thus sym- bolized are to be found in the region of space which corresponds to the symbolic mmiber in its cosmological interpretation; e.g., "oppor- tunity" in that appropriated to the nimiber 7. Aristotle then asks is the number 7, which they say is "opportunity," the same as that of which they say physical things are made, or different? E. g., is "op- portunity" a figure made up of seven visible points ? If "opportunity," "injustice," etc., are numbers, and bodies are also nimibers, we must mean something very different by "number" in the two cases. Christ, in his second edition, retains iiiv ffup-fiaii^ec and ooToq^ and, with Zeller, inserts tooto before ijdyjin line 26. This gives us the sense: "and when they say as a proof of this that each of these is a number, and that just this multitude of magnitudes happens to be already constituted in this region, because," etc. I cannot understand the implied reasoning.

^ "These things" appears now not to mean, as in the last sen- tence, opportunity, etc., but the extended figures and bodies previously referred to.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 117

place, in the attempt to discover the causes of the entities of the actual world' they introduced the notion of a second class of entities equally numer- ous with them.^ This is just as if one who wished to count certain things should fancy that while they remain fewer he will not succeed, but should first multiply them and then count. For the Ideas are pretty nearly as numerous as, or not fewer than, the things by inquiring into whose causes they advanced from actual objects to Ideas. For there is something synonymous corresponding to every group not only of substances but of all other things in which there is a One over the Many,' both in this world of actual things and in that of eternal things.

Again, none of the methods of argument by which we try to prove the existence of the Ideas

^T(u>d\ Tuiv ovTojv, "entities here" in the actual world per- ceptible by sense, as contrasted with things tliere, i. e., in the "intel- ligible world" of Plato's Ideas.

' The rest of the critique of Plato down to 991b 7, "of which we Platonists say there are not Ideas," appears again in Metaphysics, 31, chs. 4, 5, in a form which is almost verbally identical with the present chapter, except that there Aristotle does not, as here, affect by the use of the pronoun of the first person plural to be speaking as a critic from within the Platonic circle itself. This repetition is one of many indications that the Metaphysics is in no sense a literary "work," prepared by its author for circulation.

^ The "One over the Many" (?v im TznkXwv) is the single class-concept predicable of each severally of a plurality of indi- viduals.

ii8 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

really establishes the conclusion. From some of them no necessary conclusion follows; from others, it follows that there would also be Ideas in cases where we do not beHeve in them. According to the arguments drawn from the sciences/ there will be Ideas of all things of which there are sciences. According to that based on the One over the Many,^ there must be Ideas also of nega- tives, and according to that based on our ability to conceive of what has perished,^ Ideas of

' This is the argument that, since there is exact and absolute truth, there must be a corresponding class of objects of knowledge, viz., the eternal, immutable Ideas. It occurs in Plato, e. g., at Republic, 478a; Timmus, 51. Aristotle objects that there are sciences of objects for which the Platonists themselves did not postulate corresponding Ideas, viz., negatives, relatives, artificial products. These limitations do not, however, occur in the Platonic dialogues. We read in the Cratylus (389) of an Idea of shuttle, in the Republic (597) of an Idea of bed artificial products; in the Phcedo and Parmenides of Ideas of equality and bigness relations; in the Parmenides of an Idea of inequaUty a negative.

^ This appears to be what we might call the argument from the existence of a Limit, i. e., the inference of Phwdo, 74 ff, that there must, e. g., be such a tiling as absolute equality, which is never actually ex- hibited but only suggested as an ideal limit by the examples of approxi- mate equality presented by sensuous perception. Aristotle's rather shallow objection would be most strikingly expressed by putting it in the form that since o is one of the most familiar instances of a limit, the argument from the existence of a limit requires that o should exist.

' The "argument from our ability to conceive what has perished" is best illustrated by Aristotle's own previous observation in ch. 6, that Plato held that the objects referred to in definitions cannot be sensible objects, since the definition is always equally true, but all sensible things are mutable.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 119

perishable things; for there is a memory-image* of them. Besides, his most exact^ arguments partly j j^vnJ^U2 1 lead to Ideas of relatives, of which there is, accord- ing to us, no self-existing class, and partly bring the ' ' third man ' ' ' into the argument. And, speak- ing generally, the arguments for the Ideas lead to the denial of things* whose reality we Platonists

' (pdvTaaiia.

' These, according to Alexander, are the arguments which make the relation between the Idea and the corresponding class of sensible ob- jects more definite by saying that the Idea is the Original {T:apddeiy/Jia) of which the sensible thing is a copy {6/io{u>fia or fit'pirjfia), i. e., the arguments in which the Idea appears as an Ideal Limit or Standard.

' The "third man" is the difficulty known in modern logic as the "indefinite regress." We learn from Alexander that it had been originally raised by the sophist, Polyxenus. Plato himself alludes toit in Republic, 597, and explicitly states it in Parw<;m<:?e5, 132, though without formally indicating his answer to it. It runs thus: If the likeness between Socrates, Plato, and other persons proves that they are all "copies" of a common archetype, the "Idea of Man," then the Hke- ness between this Idea and Socrates must also prove that both Socrates and the Idea are "copies" of another common archetype, which will be a second and more ultimate Idea of Man; and the Ukeness between the first and second Ideas of Man proves the existence of a third Idea, which is tJmr common archetype, and so on in iitdefiuitum. (The real solution of the puzzle is that the relation between Socrates and "man" is not the same as the relation between Socrates and Plato. Socrates and Plato are both members of the class Jtien; "man" is not a member of the class "men." Hence the argument of Polyxenus and Aristotle is a sophism, and the difficulty about the "regress" does not arise except in the case of those classes which can be members of them- selves. On these classes, see Russell, Principles oj Mathematics, I., ch. X., and Appendix B.)

* The "things" in question, Alexander explains, are the con- stituent elements of the Ideas themselves, the One and the Dyad of the

I20 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

are even more concerned to maintain than that of the Ideas. For it follows from them that it is not the Dyad but number which is logically primary, that the relative is prior to the absolute, and all the other inconsistencies between the consequences which have been drawn from the theory of Ideas and its principles. Further, ac- cording to the conviction on which our Ideal theory is based, there will be Ideas not only of substances, but of much else (for there are common concepts not only in the case of substances but in other cases, and sciences not only of substances but of other entities, and there is a host of similar conse- quences). But according to rigid logic, and the

Great and Small. Aristotle contends that the theory of Ideas leads to consequences which are incompatible with the initial assumption as to these elements. E. g., if the Great and Small is one of the two con- stituents of ever}' Idea, it must be a simpler notion presupposed in every Idea and thus logically prior to all the Ideas. Therefore it must, of course, be prior to the Idea of Number. But, since you can say, e. g., '"The Great and Small are a pair oj entities" or "are two entities," and two is a number, number should be the class, or universal, of which the Dyad is one instance, and it ought to follow that nimiber is logically prior to what Plato regards as one of its simple constituents. (The reader will readily perceive that this, again, is a sophism, turning on the identification of the Indeterminate Dyad or "Variable" with the number 2. The repeated instances of this identification which occur both in this chapter and throughout book M afford a striking illustra- tion of Aristotle's deficiency in exact mathematical thought.) He further goes on to object that Plato's theory makes the "relative" prior to the "absolute." This is because the fundamental concepts of that theory, "number" and "archetype," are relative terms. (Every number or archetype is a number or archetype 0/ something.)

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 121

accepted theory of the Ideas, if things are related to

the Ideas by ''participation" there can be Ideas

only of substances. For things do not "partake"

of them per accidens; they only partake of each

Idea in so far as it is not predicated of something ^

else as a sul^gti^ute. WTiat I mean is, e. g., that ScJhi^M

if anything partakes of the Idea of ''double" it

also partakes of something eternal, but only per

accidens, for it is an accident of the Idea of

"double" to be eternal.* Hence the Ideas

must be of substances.^ But the same terms which

denote substance here^ denote it also there; or

what else can be meant by sapng that there is 991a.

besides the actual things here something which

is the unity corresponding to their multiphcity?

And if the Ideas and the things which partake of

' The point is this: You can say, e. g., "a right-hand glove and a left-hand glove arc two gloves"; thus in Platonic phrase, the gloves "partake of the Idea of " two. But though the Idea of two, Hke all Ideas, is eternal, you cannot say "these two gloves are eternal," for gloves, as we know, wear out. In the terminology of Aristotelian logic the relation of "participation," if it exists, must be between the sensible thing and the substance of the corresponding Idea, not bet%veen the thing and the accidents of the Idea.

' Reading with Bonitz in his Commentar>', p. i I4i and apparently with Alexander, ootrias in line 34 for MSS. oixria which Christ keeps The MSS. text gives the sense, "the Ideas must be substances," but this is throughout assumed by Aristotle as admitted.

' "Here" = among sensible things, "there" = among the Ideas, in the "intelligible" world, a mode of expression which became after- ward technical with the Neoplatonists.

122 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

them are members of the same class, they will have something in common. For why should duality be one and the same thing in the case of the perishable pairs and that of the pairs which though many are eternal, and not equally so in the case of the Idea of duality and a particular pair of things?* But if they are not members of the same class, they can have nothing but their name in common, and it is much as if one called both Callias and a wooden image men, without reference to any community of character in them.^

' The many pairs of things which are eternal are, of course, the instances of couples which occur in pure Mathematics (e. g., pairs of conjugate diameters, pairs of asymptotes). The argument is our old friend, the "third man." "To be a couple," he contends, is pred- icable alike of the Idea of "two" and of a sensible couple. You can say: "The Idea of 'two' and this pair of gloves are two couples." Therefore, on Platonic principles, there must be a second more ulti- mate Idea of "two," in which both the first Idea of "two" and the gloves "participate." The sophistical character of the reasoning becomes obvious when we reflect that the Idea of "two" is not itself two things, but one thing. Do not confuse this Idea of "two" with the Indeterminate Dyad.

'At this point the parallel passage of book /'/ (1079b 3) adds the following paragraph:

But if we assume that in general the universal concept coincides with the Idea (e. g., the qualification "plane figure" and the other constituents of the definition with the "Idea of the circle"), but that, in the case of the Idea, it must be further specified of what this Idea is the archetype, one has to consider whether this addition is not purely empty. To which constituent of the definition is it to be added ? To "center," to "plane," or to all alike ? For all the constituents of the essence are Ideas, e.g., "animal" and "biped." [I. e., in the defi- nition of man as a two-footed animal. Tr.] Besides, clearly it [i. e.,

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 123

Above all, it would be difficult to explain what the Ideas contribute to sensible things, whether to those which are eternaP or those which undergo generation and dissolution. For they are not the causes of any movement or change in them. But, once more, they are also of no assistance for the knowledge of other things (for the Ideas are not the substance of things; if they were, they would be in the things); nor do they contribute to their Being, since they are not present in the things which partake of them.^ If they were, they might perhaps be thought to be causes in the sense in which an admixture of white is the cause that something is white. But this line of

the proposed extra qualification by which the Idea is to be distinguished from a mere universal generic concept, viz., that it is "the archetype of a class of sensible things." Tr.] must itself be an entity, just as "plane" is an entity which must be present as a genus in all the species, [i. e., he argues that the same grounds which lead the Platonists to say that there is an Idea of "plane" of which circles, elHpses, and all the other plane figures " partake" would equally lead to the view that there is an Idea of "archetype" of which all the other Ideas "partake" a fresh appUcation of the "third man." Tr.]

' i. e., the heavenly bodies, which, according to Aristotle, are ungenerated and incorruptible.

' This is the essence of Aristotle's most telling objection to the Platonic doctrine, viz., that Plato regarded the Ideas as "separable" from the sensible things which, nevertheless, depend on them for their Being. In modern terminology the point is, that Plato holds that what we mean to assert in a typical proposition of the form "A' is a Y" (e. g., "Socrates is a man") is a relation between X (Socrates) and a second entity Y ("humanity," the "Idea of Man"). Aristotle regards this as an impossible analysis.

124 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

thought, which was first enunciated by Anaxag- oras, and repeated later by Eudoxus and others, is easily refutable, for it is an easy task to collect many impossible consequences in opposition to such a doctrine/

Once more, other things are not derived from the Ideas in any of the estabHshed senses of the term "derivation"; to call them "archetypes" and to say that other things "partake" of them is to employ empty words and poetical metaphors. For what is the agency which actually constructs things with the Idea as its model ? A thing may both be and become like something else without being imitated from it. Thus whether Socrates exists or not, there may equally be some one like Socrates, and it is clear that the case would not be altered even if Socrates were eternal. Also, there will be many archetypes, and consequently many Ideas, for the same thing; e. g., "animal" and ''biped" will be archetypes in the case of man, as well as the "Idea of Man." Further, the Ideas

' Plato's friend, Eudoxus of Cnidus, the astronomer, had at- tempted to meet the objection just mentioned by saying that things are a "mixture" in which the Idea is one ingredient. Aristotle regards this as analogous to the doctrine of Anaxagoras, according to which every thing contains some degree of all the contrasted qualities of matter, but exhibits to our senses only those of which it has most. The "consequences" are, no doubt, of the same kind as those urged in ch. 8, against Anaxagoras. Alexander says that Aristotle had developed them more at length in his lost work, "On Ideas."

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 125

will be archetypes not only of sensible things, but of Ideas themselves, e. g., the genus will be the archetype of the species contained in it. So one and the same thing will be both archetype and copy.* Besides, it may surely be regarded as 991 b. an impossibiHty that the substance of a thing and the thing of which it is the substance should be separated. So, how can the Ideas, if they are the substances of things, be separate from them?

In the Phcedd^ we are told that the Ideas are causes both of Being and of Becoming. And yet, even if the Ideas exist, the things which partake of them do not come into being unless there is something to set the process in motion; and many other things come into being, e. g., a house, a ring, of which we Platonists say there are not Ideas. Hence, clearly, it is possible for other things as well both to exist and come into being through

*He means that if from 'Socrates i? a man" you can infer the existence of an "Idea of Man" of which Socrates "partakes," you ought equally from " Man is an animal" to infer an "Idea of Animal" of which "the Idea of Man" partakes.

'Phaedo, lood: "When I am told that anything is beautiful because it has a goodly colour or shape, or anything else of the kind, I pay no attention to such talk, for it only confuses me. I cling simply, plainly, perhaps foolishly, to my own inner conviction that nothing makes a thing beautiful but the presence, or communication, whatever its nature may be, of that Ideal Beauty. Without any further assertion as to the nature of this relation, I assert merely that it is through Beauty that all beautiful things are beautiful."

126 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

the agency of causes of the same kind as those of the objects just referred to.*

Further, if the Ideas are numbers, how can they be causes? Perhaps, because things are a second set of numbers; e. g., this number is Man, that Socrates, that again Callias. But why, then, are the first set of numbers considered the causes of the others ? For it will make no difference that the one are eternal and the others not. But if the explanation is that things here are ratios between numbers e. g., a musical concord plainly, there is some one thing of which they are ratios. Now, if there is such a thing, viz., matter, manifestly the numbers themselves must be ratios of one thing to a second. I mean that, e. g., if Callias is a numerical ratio of fire, earth, water, and air, the Idea, too, must be a number of some other things which are its substrate, and the ''Ideal Man," whether a number or not, still will be a numerical ratio of certain things, and not simply

'The argument has two branches, (i) The mere existence of the Idea is not enough to guarantee that of a corresponding group of sen- sible things. (E. g., the existence of an "Idea of Man" does not secure the existence of Socrates. Socrates must have had parents, and his existence depends on certain acts of those parents.) (2) And artifi- cial products, on the other hand, certainly come into being. Yet the Platonists, according to Aristotle, say that there are no Ideas of such products. Why then, if houses and rings can come into being, though there are no Ideas of them, may the same not be true of every- thing else ?

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 127

a number, nor does it follow on these grounds that he will be a number.^

Again, one number can be composed of many other numbers, but how can one Idea be formed of many Ideas? If you say it is not composed of the numbers themselves, but of the units contained in them, e. g., those of the number 10,000, what is the relation between these units? If they are all homogeneous, many paradoxical consequences must follow; if they are not homogeneous, neither those of the same number with one another nor all with all, what can make the difference be- tween them, seeing that they have no qualities?^ Such thinking is neither rational nor consistent.

' The paragraph develops further the contention that numbers are relative terms. The argument is as follows: He suggests that Plato may have reconciled the assertions that the Ideas are Numbers and that they are the causes of things by the view that a sensible thing (e. g., the organism of Callias) is a combination of certain materials in accordance with a definite numerical law. This law would be, in Aris- totelian phrase, the " form" or " formal " cause of the thing in question. Only, in that case, the thing in question (the body of Callias) is not merely a numerical law, but a law of the combination of certain spe- cific material. Consequently, if the sensible thing (the body of Callias) is a copy of a certain archetype (the "Idea of Man"), this archetype also must contain something corresponding to the material factor in the thing, and thus even on Plato's own principles, the Idea will not be merely a "number" but a numerical law of the combination 0/ cer- tain material. There seems to be an allusion to the formation of the human organism out of materials which are definite compounds of the four "elements," as described in the Timoeus.

^ Aristotle's point is, that any two numbers can be added together and their sum will be a third number of the same kind. But Ideas,

128 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

Again, it becomes necessary to construct a second kind of number which is the object of Arithmetic^ and all the studies which have been called " intermediate." How or out of what principles can this be constructed ? And on what grounds must it be regarded as "intermediate" between things here and the ideal numbers?* Again, each of the uHits in the Dyad^ must be

or class-concepts, he thinks, cannot be added. If they are num- bers, they must be numbers composed of units which, unlike those of Arithmetic, are not all of the same kind, and therefore cannot always be added so as to produce a resultant of the same kind as the factors. He thinks that you may then suppose either that each of the units which compose one and the same "Ideal nvimber" may be of the same kind as all the other units of that number, but different in kind from any of the units of a different " Ideal number, " or that even the units of one and the same "Ideal number" may be all different in kind from one another, the former being the more natural hypothesis. The two forms of the supposition, which are here curtly dismissed, are discussed at length in M, ch. 7, 8, loSia i-io83a 20. The reader will see that Aristotle's philosophy of nimiber is doubly defective, since (i) he has no conception of the dependence' of arithmetical addition on the more fundamental process of logical addition (for which see Russell, Principles 0} Mathematics, I., ch. XII.); (2) and he has, also, no conception of any class of numbers except the integers. (On this point, seeMilhaud, Les Philosophes-Ceometres de la Grece, pp. 359-365, who well asks by what addition of integers Aristotle could have obtained such numbers as a/ 2, a/ 2,)

' For a detailed attack on the conception of mathematical ob- jects as "intermediate" between Ideas and sensible things, see M. ch. 2, p. 1076a 37 ff.

* I. e., the Indeterminate Dyad of the Great and Small. The argu- ment is, that since this is a dyad or "pair, " it must consist of two mem- bers; whence, then, are these derived? (You must not say that they are repetitions of the other element, the One, because in the Platonic

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 129

derived from a prior Dyad; but this is impossible. Again, why is a number of units when formed ^^^ ^' into a collection one thing ?^ Again, in addi- .

tion to all this, if the units differ, the Platonists^ ^ tw*-*^ have followed the example of those who maintain four or two elements. Each of these thinkers gives the name of element not to their common substrate, e. g., body but to fire and earth, whether they have a common substrate, viz., body, or not. But the One is in fact spoken of as if it were as homogeneous as fire or water. But if it is homogeneous in this sense, the numbers

system the "Great and Small" is regarded as being logically no less ultimate and elementary than the One.) Here, again, we have, as Bonitz observes, an unfair identification of the "IndetemiinatejDyad" with the number 2. It is only the latter, not the former, which can be said to consist of two units. And even in the case of the latter such an expression is a loose and inaccurate way of saying that 2 is the number determined by the addition of i to i, or the number of the terms of a class formed by uniting in one class the terms of the classes a and h, when a and h each have only one term and their terms are not identical.

^i. e., each Idea is one thing or unit, an entity corresponding to one determinate class or type. How then, can it also be a number, which is a collection of units? Cf. //, 1044a 2, where the same com- plaint is made that the Platonists cannot explain what it is that makes a number ojie thing, and My 1082a 15, where he asks, "how can the nxmiber 2 be an entity distinct from its two units?" This and many other passages of M show how very literally and naively Aristotle conceives of integers as formed by addition. WTiat he does not see is, that "addition is not primarily a method of forming numbers, but of forming classes or collections. If we add B io A we do not obtain the number 2, but we obtain A and B, which is a collection of two terms, or a couple." (Russell, op- cit. p. 135.)

I30 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

cannot be substances; rather, it is manifest that if there is a self-existing One and this One is a first principle, "one" is an equivocal term/ In any other case it is an impossibility.

When we^ wish to refer our substances to their principles we derive length from the Short and Long, a special case of the Small and Great, the plane from the Broad and Narrow, body from the High and Low. Yet, how can the line be contained in the plane, or the line and plane in the solid ? The Broad and Narrow is a different genus from the High and Low. So, just as num- bers are not contained in these classes, because the Many and Few is a different class from them, clearly no other of the higher genera will be con- tained in the lower. ^ Nor, again, is the Broad

* i. e., the kind of number meant by the Platonists when they speak of their Ideas as numbers must be something quite different from what the arithmetician means by number.

^i. e., "we Platonists."

^ The argument is aimed at the Platonic application of the prin- ciples of the One and the Great and Small to deiine geometrical exten- sion in one, two, three dimensions. The point is, that whereas, according to Aristotle, a solid contains surfaces, a surface lines, and a line points, this could not be the case on the Platonic principles, accord- ing to which each of the three dimensions consists of magnitudes of a different kind. (Cf. M, 9, 1085a 7-31.) Hence, he holds, a Platonist ought not to be able to define a plane in terms of the definition of a straight line, nor a solid in terms of the definition of a plane, or vice versa. Now, Aristotle holds that you can do the latter. A plane is, e. g., the boundary of a soUd; a straight line is the boundary o{ a plane (as we should say, the intersection of two planes). This is what he

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 131

the genus of which the High is a species, for if it were so, body would be a kind of plane.

Again, how will it be possible for points to "be in" figures? Plato, in fact, rejected this class of entities as a mere fiction of the geometers. He used to speak of them as the "beginning of the line," for which he often employed the expression "indivisible line." But even these lines must have a limit, so that the same argument which proves the existence of the line proves, also, that of the point.*

means by planes being "in" solids, and lines "in" planes. He does not, of course, mean that, as the Pythagoreans had thought, a soHd is actu- ally made up of superposed laminfe, or a plane of juxtaposed strips. The argument is, however, fallacious; since, e. g., a plane may quite well be, as the Platonists held, a different kind of magnitude from a straight line and yet be definable in terms of the definition of a straight line. Aristotle has, in fact, been led astray by his inadequate theory of definition as being exclusively by genus and difference. "Higher" genera means, of course, those which require for their conception a higher degree of abstraction and analysis.

* Aristotle is referring to a view, known from the commentators to have been held by Xenocrates, and here attributed by him to Plato himself, that there are really no such entities as points, what we call a point being, in fact, not a magnitude but the "starting point" i/^PX^i) or "beginning" of a magnitude, viz., of the line. There is no trace of this doctrine in the dialogues of Plato, and the imperfect tense {ixdXti) shows that Aristotle is referring not to any Platonic passage, but to verbal statements made by Plato in his lectures. Since the view in question was adopted by Xenocrates, the actual president of the Academy during Aristotle's activity in Athens as a teacher, it is natural that he should have treated it to special criticism; among the extant works ascribed to him there is, in fact, a special tract, "On

132 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

To speak generally, though it is the business of wisdom to discover the cause of visible things, we have neglectedth at task (for we have nothing to say about the cause by which change is initiated), but in the fancy that we are describing their sub- stance we assert the existence of a second class of substances, though our explanation of the way in which they are substances oj the former set is empty verbiage, for ''participation," as I have said, is nothing at all. Nor do the Ideas stand in any connection with the kind of cause which we observe in the practical^ sciences, the cause jor the sake oj which all Mind and all Nature act, and which we have included among our first principles. tuoA^AfiC Mathematics has been termed by our present- day thinkers into the whole of Philosophy, in

Indivisible Lines. ' * Plato's difl&culty, no doubt, was that the point has

^ no dimensions; it is a zero magnitude. The error of refusing to admit

tt~M« J«<*«»^ t^^ point, or zero dimension, is exactly analogous to the universal

^ error of Greek arithmeticians in regarding i , not o, as the first of the

iljr n** **^ integers. Though, since the definition of a point, often cited by Aristotle

^ as a "unit having position," seems to come from Pythagorean and

W^** r*^ Platonic sources (Cf. 31, 8, 1084b 26, 33), it seems possible that

^ ^ , 1^ Aristotle (and Xenocrates ?) may have misunderstood what Plato

r\^ " ^^ meant by calling the point an "indivisible line," as is maintained by

'ISLm* - ^ Milhaud, op. cit. p. 341-2. The reader will note that, though

^'^ ^ ,. Aristotle's conclusion that Geometry requires the point is sound,

fuj,%^uJ^ ''^ T his argument is a petitio principii, since it assumes the existence

.f^ of the limit.

' I follow Zeller in making the necessary addition of noirjTixds Jt J ijnl'^ ^^■•'^efore iTt'-irr-^ixas in line 29.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 133

spite of their declaration that it ought to be stud- ied for the sake of something further.* 992 b.

Besides, we may fairly regard the entity which they assume as .matter as being more properly of a mathematical kind, and as being rather a predi- cate and a specific difference of substance and matter than identical with matter itself. I mean the Great and the Small; just as the physicists, when speaking of rarity and density, say that these are the primary specific differences of the material substrate, for they are a kind of excess and defect. And as to motion, if these elements^ are to constitute motion, plainly the ideas will be in motion f if they are not to constitute it, whence has it come? Thus the whole study of physical Nature is abolished. And even the proof, which is fancied to be so easy, that all things are one, does not follow. Their method of ''exposition,"* even if one grants all their assump-

' The reference is specially to the place assigned to Mathematics as a propaedeutic to the study of the Ideas in Republic, VII., particularly to 53id: "All these are mere preludes to the hymn which has to be learned. For you surely do not consider those who are proficients in them as dialecticians."

^ viz., the Great and Small.

' Because the Great and Small is a constituent of every Idea. That the Ideas should "be in motion" is impossible, on Platonic prin- ciples, because one chief characteristic of them is their immutabilit)'.

*The method here and elsewhere called by Aristotle "exposi- tion" {exdsaiqi) is the familiar Platonic procedure of inferring from

134 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

tions, does not prove that all things are one, but only that there is a self-existing One, and does not even prove this unless it is granted that the universal is a genus; but in som,e cases that is impossible. And as for the objects they consider logically posterior to the numbers, viz., lines and planes and solids, no rational grounds can be pro- duced to show how they exist or can exist, nor what character they possess. They cannot be Ideas (for they are not numbers), nor the "interme- diate" class of objects (for these are mathematical figures), nor yet can they be identical with perish- able things. Manifestly, we have here, again, a fresh and a fourth class of objects.^

In general, it is impossible to discover the ele-

(jT the existence of many individual things possessing some common pred-

** icate the existence of a single supersensible entity, the Idea, which is their common archetjT)e^ He objects (i) that the argument, in any case, does not prove that all the individual things are one thing, but J ;i °"^y ^^^''' b^^i^^ them, there is one ideal archet3^e of v?hich they are all ^4a. */'*^ copies; (2) it does not even prove this unless the common predicate

I i J * l\^ ^^ *^^ name of a " real kind " or genus. This is a corollary from his

V M- "^ previous conclusion that if there are Ideas they can only be Ideas of

u3

C Ac^yv>*l

substances.

, » ' The point is this: The Plato nists hold that the many lines.

Tit planes, solids, of Geometry are copies of certain single archetypal

IP . I— ^ < entities the line, the plane, ilte solid. These are the "objects pos-

_ terior to the "Numbers" here spoken of. But what are these objects ?

II& 6'^'*^, ^°* Ideas (since they are not numbers, and every Idea is a number); not geometrical figures (since geometrical figures are copies of them); not physical things, since they are immutable. Thus they must be a fourth class of objects, not provided for in the Platonic classification of

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 135

merits of existing things if one does not first distin- guish the different "senses of existence," especially when the inquiry is directed towards the problem of what elements existing things are composed. For one certainly cannot discover what are the elements of which activity or passivity or straight- ness is composed. If the problem is soluble at all, it is only soluble in the case of substances.^ So it is an error to ask after, or to think one has found, the elements of everything. How, indeed,

objects into Ideas, mathematical objects, and sensible things. This argiiment is further developed in great detail in ch. 2, of book 31, given in appendix D.

> He concludes his polemic by an attack on the general theory of the nature of science which is tacitly impUed in the Platonic doc- trine, viz., that the objects of all the sciences are composed of the same constituent elements. He has already explained that Plato thought that the elements of the Ideas are the elements of ever>-thing. It follows that there is ultimately only one science, viz.. Dialectic, which, as we learn from Republic, VI., 511, cognizes the ultimate axioms from which all scientific truth can be deduced. Aristotle holds that there is no such supreme science of first principles; every science has its own special subject-matter, and consequently its own special a.-doms {Analytica Poskriora, I., 76a 16). In this passage he urges two objec- ions to the Platonic view. ( i ) Analysis into constituent elements is only possible in the case of substances. In a substance you have always the two constituent logical elements of matter and jorm (which appear in its definition as genus and difference), but these elements cannot be found in a quality, an action, or a state. Cf. H. 10444b 8: "Things which exist in nature, but are not substances, have no mat- ter, but their substrate is their substance. E. g., what is the cause of an eclipse? What is its matter ? There is none, but the moon is the thing affected." He means, then, that Plato thinks that in the end all objects of knowledge are made of the same ingredients, and

136 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

could one possibly learn the elements of every- thing ? For it is clear that one could not possibly have been in previous possession of any informa- tion at all. Just as he who is learning geometry may very well have previous knowledge about other things, but has no previous acquaintance with the truths which belong to that science, and which he is about to learn, so it is in all other cases. So, if there is, as some assert, a universal science of everything, he who learns it must have no previous acquaintance with anything. And yet all learning is effected through previous acquaintance with some or all of the matters con- therefore there is only one science of them all; but Aristotle says there is no sense in asking what qualities or activities are made of. (2) The second objection depends on the principle that all learning of anything depends on and requires previous knowledge. (See Appendix A.) To learn the truth by devionstration, you must pre- viously know the premises of the proof; to learn it from a defi^iition, you must know the meaning of the terms employed; to learn it by induction, i. e., comparison of instances, you must previously be acquainted with the individual instances. Hence if all truths con- stituted a single science, before learning that science you would know no truths at all, and therefore the process of learning itself would be impossible. To meet the retort which a Platonist, who held wdth Plato that all knowledge is really recollection, would be sure to make, viz., that the knowledge of the ultimate axioms is "innate," and not acquired at all (Cf. Plato, Meno, 8ic, etc.), he argues that if we had such innate cognitions we could not be unconscious of having them the same argument afterward employed by Locke.

As an argument against the doctrine of an all-embracing science the reasoning seems a pure peliiio principii, since it merely goes to prove the necessity of some self-evident truths.

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 137

cerned. This is true both of learning from demonstration and of learning from definitions. The parts which compose the definition must be previously known and familiar. The same is true, also, of learning from induction. But if it 993 a. be suggested that this knowledge is really innate, it is surely a mystery how we can possess the most excellent of sciences and yet be unconscious of the fact. Besides, how are we to recognize what existence consists of? How can the result be established?^ There is a difficulty implied here, since the same doubt might be suggested as about certain syllables. Some say that the syllable ZA consists of r, j, and A, others that it is a distinct sound, different from those already familiar. Besides, how could one become acquainted with the objects of sense-perception, without pos- sessing the corresponding form of sense-percep- tion ? Yet, this ought to be possible if all things

M. e., even when you have analysed everything back into its simple elements, how are you to recognize the fact that they are simple and that the analysis cannot be carried any further? an objection which, one might think, is as much or as little applicable to Aristotle's own analysis of a thing into matter and form as to Plato's analysis of everything into the One and the Great and the Small. The illus- tration about the analysis of a syllable into its simple constituent sounds is from Plato, Thcaetetus, 203a, where, however, the application of it is rather different Aristotle's point is, that while some gram- marians regard the sound of the Greek letter Z (which appears to have . . been equivalent to our A) as simple, others hold that it can be ' ^ analysed further into the two sounds of - and A.

138 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

are composed of the same constituent elements/ as composite articulate sounds are composed of their own special elements.^

CHAPTER X.

It is clear, then, even from the preceding review, that all philosophers seem to be investigating the forms of cause enumerated in our discourses on Physics, and that we can specify no further form of cause beside these. But their treatment of them was obscure, and though in one sense all the causes had been previously recognized, in another sense this had not been done at all. For at first, and in its beginnings, owing to its youth, the earliest philosophy resembled in its utterances on all topics the lisping speech of an infant. Thus even Empedocles says that the existence of botie depends on a ratio, ^ but this ratio is, in fact, the

' i. e., if, for instance, a visible object, such as a shade or color, is ultimately constituted by a combination of purely logical categories, like the One and the Great and Small (as must be the case if the "elements of the Ideas are the elements of all things"), a Platon'c philosopher, even though blind from birth, ought to be able to have "pure anticipated cognitions" of all the colors of the spectrum.

' This clause is plausibly regarded by Christ as a misplaced gloss

onthewordsof the sentence: "Some say that the syllable Z, J,

and A," above.

' Xoyoq, The reference is to Empedocles, iggff , where bone is said to consist of fixed proportions of the elementary bodies. The

ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS. 139

essential nature or essence^ of the object. But it follows with equal necessity that there must also be a ratio for flesh, and every other individual thing, or for none at all. This, then, and not the matter, of which Empedocles speaks, viz., fire, and earth and water and air, will be the true ground of the existence of flesh and bone and everything else. If another had explained this he would have had no alternative but to admit it, but he did not express it clearly himself. These and similar points, then, have been explained above, but we may now return to the consideration of the diffi- culties which might be raised about these same topics. Perhaps a study of them may pave the way for an answer to our subsequent difficulties.

point is, simply, that Empedocles is recognizing that what a thing is depends primarily on its jorm or formal cause, or, as we should say, the law of its composition, and not merely on the nature of the stuff of which it is made.

*To Ti ^v elvac xa\ rj ouffta.

APPENDIX.

APPENDIX.

On the Cognition of Universal Axioms, as a product of Experience. (Cf. Met., A, i, gSoa 27-b29, 9, 992b 25flf.) Analytica Postcriora, 2, 71a 1-16.

All instruction and all processes of intellectual' learning depend upon the presence of antecedent cognitions. This will become manifest if we consider the various cases seri- atim} The mathematical sciences and every one of the other arts are acquired in this manner. The same is true of logic, both syllogistic and inductive; in both cases the instruction is derived from antecedent cognitions. In the former premises are assumed, with the implication that their sense is understood; in the latter a universal is estab- lished by the manifest truth of the individual instances.

' The qualifying epithet is intended to exclude cognition through immediate sense-perception on the one hand and the immediate intuition of ultimate axioms on the other.

^ The argument which follows is a typical Aristotelian "induc- tive syllogism," i e., a demonstration that a predicate a belongs univer- sally to a genus A by showing that it belongs separately to each of the subordinate species into which A can be exhaustively subdivided. Mathematical and scientific reasoning, Xoyot or philosophic science not aided by sensuous diagrams, rhetorical reasoning, are treated as the three species of the genus "inferential knowledge."

143

144 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

Rhetorical arguments, again, produce conviction in the same way, either by means of examples (and this is induc- tion) or by means of enthymemes^ (and this is syllogism). The antecedent cognition necessary may be of two kinds. In some cases we require previous recognition of the truth of a statement, in others, previous understanding of the sense of a term; in others again, both are needed. E. g., in the case of the proposition that "every proposition can either be truly affirmed or truly denied" ' we have to pre- suppose the truth of a statement; in the case of "triangle," the meaning of a term; in the case of "the number i," both the meaning of the term and the existence of the thing denoted.^

Analytica Posteriora, II., 19, 99b 20-ioob 17.

We have already said that it is impossible to have scien- tific knowledge as the result of demonstration without cog- nition of the ultimate axiomatic principles.' But a diffi- culty might be raised as to the cognition of these axioms themselves. Is it of the same kind as the cognition of dem- onstrated truth. Tr.], or of a different kind ? Are both the objects of science, or is the one the object of science, the other of a different form of cognition? Also, does the cognition of axioms make its appearance in consciousness, having previously been absent, or is it unconsciously present

* "Enthymemes" not in the modern but in the Aristotelian sense of "inference from Ukelihood or presumptive evidence."

'This is meant for a formulation of the law of Excluded Middle.

'rdij 7zp<oTa': ^PX"^^ '^^'^ Aixioouq^ "first and immediate princi- ples," i. e., axioms incapable of being syllogistically deduced, through a middle term, from any more general and ultimate principles.

APPENDIX. 145

from the first ?* It is certainly strange if we possess it from the first. For it follows that we possess cognitions which are more accurate than demonstration, and yet are uncon- scious of the fact. Yet, if we do not at first possess themt but afterward acquire them, how come we to apprehend and learn them, except on a basis of antecedent cognition? For that, as was said in speaking of demonstrative proof, is impossible. It is plain, then, that we can neither possess them from the first nor could they appear in consciousness if we were ignorant of them and had no disposition to acquire them. One is thus driven to conclude that we have a certain faculty of acquiring them, but not of such a kind as to rank higher than demonstrated truth in respect of accuracy.^ Now, such a faculty is obviously present in all animals. They have a congenital faculty of discrimination, which is called sense-perception. On the occurrence of sensation there supervenes in some animals retention of Wtj ^ (^ '^^^Itt the sense-percept, in others not. Where it does not occiu universany, or with respect to certain sensations, the animal has no cognition beyond the sensation; where it does occur r*»*#li»»

* The two alternatives, both of which he finds unsatisfactory, are pure Empiricism and the Platonic doctrine of recollection, which he interprets as a theor\' of "innate ideas." He proceeds to mediate between these alternatives much as Leibniz did between the doctrines of Locke and Descartes.

' TouTU)'/j in line 33, I take to mean rajy aTZodei^icav. The meaning of the "accuracy" or "exactness" here spoken of will be perceived by reference to Analytica Post., I., 27, 87a 33, where we are told that a science which deals with universal relations in abstraction is more "exact" than one which considers their appli- cation to a special subject-matter (e. g., Arithmetic than Harmonics), and a science which makes few initial postulates than one which makes more (e. g., Arithmetic than Geometry).

^

146 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

the animal can, after sensation is over, preserve some result of it in consciousness. When this process is frequently repeated a further distinction makes its appearance; in some animals such retention leads to rational cognition, in others not. Thus, as I say, sense-perception gives rise to memory, and repeated memories of the same object to ex- perience; for the numerically many memories form a single experience. And experience, i. e., any establishment in consciousness of a universal, or one over and above the many, which is a point of identity present in them all,* leads to the principles of Art and Science; of Art if it is concerned vi^ith Production, of Science if it is concerned with Being.

These axiomatic cognitions thus are neither there from the first in a determinate form nor yet are they derived from other cognitions of a higher type,^ but from sense-percep- tion. The process is like what occurs in battle after a rout, when first one man makes a stand, and then a second and a third follow his example, and so at last order is estab- lished. The constitution of consciousness is such as to permit of this process.^

Let me repeat an explanation which has already been

1 This clause is added to show that by the "one over and above the many" he means merely a subjective "general concept," not a Platonic Idea.

^ yvu)(TTCxu)T£()(ov "naturally more knowable," i. e., logically simpler and therefore more ultimate.

^ The point of the comparison lies in the fact that in the rally order and discipline come to be spontaneously re-established with- out the direct ''ssuing of instructions to that effect by a superior. So, owing to the implicit generalising character of all cognition, axioms come spontaneously to be recognized in consequence of our percep- tion of their validity in special applications, vdthout any process of conscious formal deduction.

APPENDIX. 147

given, though without due precision. When a conviction has been established about any class of objects which are indistinguishable in kind, we have the earliest universal in consciousness; (for in fact, though the object perceived is an individual thing, sense perception is of the universal; e. g., of man, not of the man Callias). Generalisations are then established among these classes, and so we proceed, until we come to the establishment of the unanalysable universals. E. g., we pass from generalisations about "such and such a species of animal" to generalisations about "ani- mal," and treat that concept in the same way. For even sense-perception in this way gives rise to universal cogni- tions.*

* Translation of the highly condensed expressions of this para- graph necessarily involves some amount of interpretative para- phrase, but I have endeavoured to keep as closely as possible to the actual words of the text. The key to its meaning is given by the parenthetical remark about the implicit universality of sense-percep- tion. The spontaneous inductive process which leads from the simplest generalisations about the more obvious classes of sensible objects, through axiomata media to use Bacon's familiar phrase to the most universal of axioms, which are quite incapable of adequate representation by sensible illustrations, depends for its possibility upon the principle that though the object cognized in sense-per- ception itself is always a particular individual (the man Callias), the content of the perception, that which is cognized about the object, is always a universal, or complex of universals. The use of the expression d/iep^ "indivisibles" (rendered in the text "unanalysable") for the axioms of highest generality is, I suppose, explained by the fact that in Aristotle's theory of definition by genus and difference, the genus appears as a "part" of the intension of the species. (Meta- physics, A 25, 1023b 24: "Hence the genus is also called a part of the species, though in another sense the species is part of the genus. ") Thus an "unanalysable" genus is one which cannot be regarded as a species of a higher class, an indefinable summum genus or highest universal.

148 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

Thus it is clear that we need to apprehend ultimate axioms by a process of induction.^ And since of the intel- lectual conditions by which we perceive truth some are always truthful, while others admit of error (e. g., Opinion and Computation, whereas Science and Rational Intuition are always truthful); since, further. Rational Intuition^ is the only type of cognition which is more exact than Science, while the principles of demonstration are "more knowable" ' than the results of demonstration, and all Science involves inference, the cognition of axiomatic principles cannot be Science. Hence, since the only form of cognition which can have a higher truth than Science is Rational Intuition, it must be by Rational Intuition that axiomatic principles are cognized. This result follows, also, from the considera- tion that since the principles of demonstration are not them- selves demonstration, those of Science cannot be themselves Science. So, if we have no type of true cognition except Science, Rational Intuition must be the principle from which Science starts.*

Eihica Nicomachea, vi.-xi., 1143a 35 h$.

* Induction, that is, in the Socratic sense; i. e., the general princi- ple of the axiom is made clear to us in consequence of our previous recognition of its validity in particular classes of instances.

'vt»t)?, "Mind;" i. e., a cognition which is at once rational and universal, and also like sense-perception at the other end of the series, immediate See the passage from the Ethics, which immediately follows.

^i. e., "naturally, in the logical order of concatenation of truths, more knowable;" that is, are simpler and more ultimate universal truths.

* Aristotle's view is thus twofold. The process by which the individual mind, as a fact in its psychological history, comes by the apprehension of the axioms is one of generalising induction from

APPENDIX. 149

It is Rational Intuition which apprehends the ultimates m both directions. For both the first and the last terms of our reasoning are apprehended by Rational Intuition, not by discursive reasoning. In demonstrations this intuition is of the primary and immutable principles, in the study of questions of conduct it is of contingent ultimate facts and minor premises, for these are the starting-point of pur- posive action, since its universal rules are based on par- ticular cases. Of these cases, then, we must have an im- mediate perception, and that is Rational Intuition.

B.

The Four Senses of Cause.

Aristotle, Metaphysics, -I 2, ioi3a24 h2S. = Physics ^3. 194b 23-i95a 26.

A cause signifies in one of its meanings that out oj which anything is formed and which continues to exist in it; e. g., the bronze of the statue, the silver of the goblet, and the universal classes of these materials; in another meaning

examples. We are individually led up to the recognition of the princi- ple by being familiarised with examples of its truth in concrete cases. But the "induction" in no sense proves the axiom; it merely calls attention to it. (Cf. 91b 33. "He who produces an example does not prove the conclusion, though he does point aid something.)" The axiom is, in fact, neither proved nor provable. \\'hen the requi- site illustrations have been produced, you simply have directly to see what the implied principle is, and, if you do not see it, no proof can make you see. Aristotle's view thus turns out to be simply the Platonic doctrine of "innate ideas" minus its imaginative psycholog- ical background of pre-existence. Whether the removal of this background is an improvement is a point on which opinions may possibly differ. The ultimate germ of the whole theon' is the treat- ment of association as a source of suggestion in Phcedo, p. 73 ff.

ISO ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

it signifies the jorm and the archetype/ i. e., the formula expressive of the essential nature^ and its universal classes. E. g., that of the octave is the ratio 2:1, and universally number and the constituent parts of the definitory formula are causes of this kind. It signifies also the first source of change or of rest, e. g., the giver of advice is the cause of its consequences, the father of his offspring, and universally the agent of the act, the producer of change of the change produced. Also, the term is used in the sense of the end, i. e., the purpose for the sake of which anything is done; e. g., health is the cause, in this sense, of walking. For why does the man take walks? We answer, "in order to keep in health," and when we have said this we believe ourselves to have assigned the cause of his action. This applies also to what occurs under the agency of another in the process of attaining the end; e. g., in the case of health, the lower- ing treatment, the purgation, the physician's drugs and im- plements; they are all there for the sake of the end, though there is this difference among them that some of them are implements, others their effects. These, then, are the prin- cipal different senses of the term "cause." It follows that since the term is an equivocal one, there may be many causes of the same effect, and that not merely in an acci- dental sense. Thus, e. g., both the sculptor's art and the bronze are causes of the statue, and that not in respect of some further characteristic but in its character of a statue. But they are not its causes in the same sense of the term; the one is its cause in the sense of its material, the other in the sense of the source of movement. Things may also be reciprocally causes of each other; for instance, exertion

' TzapddefjTfia. 'ro Ti rjv elvai.

APPENDIX. 151

of good bodily condition, and this of exertion, but not in the same sense; the one is cause in the sense of end, the other in the sense of the source of motion.

Further, the same thing may in some cases be the cause of opposite results. When a thing, by its presence, is the cause of a given result, we sometimes regard it as being, by its absence, the cause of the opposite result. Thus the cause of a vessel's capsizing is said to be the absence of the captain, whose presence was the cause of her previous safety. And here both the presence and its negation are causes in the sense of sources of motion.

All the senses of cause which have now been enumerated fall into four most obvious classes. Letters of the alphabet are causes of syllables, raw materials are causes of manu- factured products, fire, earth, and the like of bodies, the parts of the whole, the premises of the conclusion, in the sense that they are the factors from which they are formed. Of such factors, some are of the character of the substrate, e. g., the parts, others of that of the essential nature,* e. g., the totality, the synthesis of parts, the form.' The seed, the physician, the giver of advice, and universally the agent, are all instances of the source of change or quiescence. Other examples are instances of the end or good to which something else is relative. For that for the sake of which something takes place claims to be the best state and the end of something else. (We need not raise the question

' Tu ^v elvat.

'The structure of the Greek sentence is awkward, since it opens at "letters of the alphabet." as if reference were going to be made to the material "factor," or substrate, only, and is then unexpectedly enlarged so as to include the "form" and "essential nature" under the general rubric of "factors from which things are formed."

152 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

whether it ought to be called the real good or the apparent good.)'

' Aristotle's account of the Four Causes may be most readily understood by bearing in mind the etymological connection of the word atrtov ahia, "cause," with the adjective al'rcuq, "respon- sible for," "accountable for." The aiTtuv of any state of things is that to which, in the EngHsh vernacular idiom, the state of things in question can be "blamed." Now, when we ask, "what is respon- sible for the fact that such and such a state of things now exists, there are four obvious partial answers to be given, corresponding to the four Aristotelian senses of " cause." We may mention ( i ) the fac- tors out of which the thing has been constructed the matter or material cause of the thing; (2) the law according to which those fac- tors have been combined the jorni or formal cause; (3) the agent with whose initiating impulse the process of combination or develop- ment began the source 0] motion or efficient cause, (4) the conscious and deliberate, or instinctive and subconscious purpose which the process of development has realized the end or final cause. Had any one of these four been different, the resultant state of things would also have been in some degree different. Hence they all are "responsible for" the result, that is, are lis causes. The most obvious illustrations, given as such by Aristotle, are to be found in the case of artificial products of human skill, such as, e. g., a statue. The statue would not be what it is if (a) its matter had been different, e. g., if the sculptor had used bronze or wood instead of marble; a (b) if its form had been different, e. g., if he had hewed the marble into the linea- ments of Hercules instead of Apollo; (c) or if the material had been subjected to a different series of movements on the part of the artificer, e. g., if he had cut it into blocks for pediments, or (4) if he had not aimed at producing this result but some other; e. g., if he or his patron had wanted an obelisk, and not a statue. It seems clear, however, that the analysis was originally suggested rather by Aris- totle's interest as a biologist in the facts of organic development. Suppose we ask, e. g., what was requisite in order that there should now be an oak on this particular spot. We may say (i) there must previously have been a germ from which the oak has grown, and this germ must have had certain actual physical and chemical properties characteristic of the germs from which oaks in particular grow, or there

APPENDIX. 153

C.

A Popular Resume of the main arguments against the Platonic Ideas, with special reference to the "Idea of Good."

Ethica Nicomachea, i, 6, io6a n by.

It is perhaps better to examine the notion of a universal good, and to state the difficulties it raises, though such an investigation is distasteful to me, owing to my personal friendship for the inventors of the doctrine of Ideas. Still, it will surely be allowed that it is commendable and even obligatory in defence of truth to abandon even one's own cherished convictions, especially in a philosopher. For

would have been no oak. This is the material cause. (2) This germ, though in many respects perhaps not distinguishable from those of other species, must have followed certain special laws in its development; it must have had an initial tendency to grow in the way characteristic of oaks, not that of elms or planes, etc. This is the Jorm or formal cause. (3) There must have been an initial movement by which the germ was brought into contact with the external surroundings requisite in order that the process of develop- ment may begin an efficient cause. (4) And there must be an uhimate or final stage in the process, a stage in which the germ is no longer developing into something that one day will be an oak, but actually has grown into an adult oak. This is the oid or final cause, in the perfectly hteral sense of "end," as the last stage of the process. Aristotle's biological interest leads him to conceive of this final stage of the development as in all cases a conscious or subconscious pur- pose immanent throughout all the previous stages. (Thus in organic development the formal and final causes regularly tend to coalesce in a single conception of an immanent law of growth, which is at the same time a teleological law of a thing's purposive activity.) It will be seen that individual agency is an indispensable element in his notion of causation, and that he has no sense of "cause" exactly corresponding to the famihar modern notion of a mere uniform law of the sequence of events. For an excellent brief exposition of the sub- ject, see Siebeck, Aristoteles (Frohmann's Classiker der Philosophie, Vol. 8, pp. 32-42).

154 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

though both are dear to us, it is a sacred duty to give the preference to truth.* Well, the devisers of the theory did not profess to recognize Ideas of aggregates in which there is an order of priority and posteriority (and for this reason they constructed no Idea of the class of numbers). Now, "good" is predicated alike in the categories of Sub- stance, of Quality, and of Relation. But the absolute, i. e., Substance, is logically prior to the Relative (which seems rather to be an accessory or accident of substance), so that there cannot be a common Idea applicable to all these instances.

Again, "good" has as many meanings as "Being." It is predicated in the categories of Substance, e. g., of God or Mind; in that of Quality, e. g.,of the virtues; in that of Quantity, e. g., of the due mean; in that of Relation, e.g., of the useful; in that of Time, e. g.,of the favourable oppor- tunity; in that of Place, e. g.,of favourable climate, etc. So it clearly has no one single, universal sense. If it had, it would not be predicable in all the categories, but only in one.

Again, since the things which fall under a single Idea form the objects of a single science, there ought to be a single science of all "goods" universally. But there are in fact many sciences even of the "goods" which come under a single category. E. g., the favourable opportunity in war is the object of Strategy, in disease of Medicine; the due mean in diet is the object of Medicine, in exercise of Gym- nastics.

' He adroitly excuses his attack by the same apology which Plato had employed for his attack on Homer in Republic, 595c: "I must speak, said I, and yet I am restrained by the love and admiration I have felt for Homer ever since my childhood. . . . But, after all, a man should not be honoured at the expense of truth; so, as I say, I must speak."

APPENDIX. 155

One may also be puzzled even to know what they mean by an "Ideal so-and-so,' ' since it is one and the same definition of man which applies alike to the "Ideal Man" and to an ordinary man. In so far as both are "men," there is no difiference between them. Consequently, there is no differ- ence either in the case of "good." Nor, again, will the Idea be any more truly good because it is eternal, just as a thing which lasts a long time is not on that account any whiter than one which only lasts a day.

D.

The alleged Difficulty in the Connection of Mathematics with the Doctrine of Ideas. (Cf. A, 9, g92b 12-17.)

Metaphysics, M^ 2, 1076b 11 39.

Yet, it is not even possible that there should be such sep- arate and independent' entities. For if, over and above the solids our senses perceive, there is to bea further set of solids separate from and independent of the former, and logically prior to them, manifestly there must also be separate and independent planes, over and above the planes our senses perceive, and similarly in the case of points and lines; it is all part of the same theory. But, so much being admitted, once again, there must be yet further separate and inde- pendent planes, lines, and points, over and above those con- tained in geometrical solid figures. For isolated entities are logically prior to the same entities in combination; and if

* xejj^WjOj<T/jic>ac, " separatedj " i. c, existing as distinct objective entities, not merely as products of subjective mental abstraction without a real separate existence of their own. T have employed the double expression "separate and independent" to represent the one Greek word, which it is, however, very tempting to translate simply by " transcendent."

156 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

bodies which are not perceptible to the senses are logically prior to bodies which are so perceptible, it follows by the same argument that independent, self-existing planes are logically prior to the planes of the motionless' solids. So that these planes and lines are classes distinct from those postulated along with the separate and independent solids.

X^The latter are postulated with the mathematical solid figures;

^ the former are logically prior to these figures./*

Similarly once more, the planes just referred to will con- tain lines, and by the same reasoning there must be yet other lines and points prior to these, and besides the points of these "prior" lines there must be yet other points, prior to them, but beyond which there is no further prior class of points. Now, surely, this accumulation of entities becomes an absurdity. For it follows that there is only one class of solids besides those our senses perceive, but three such classes of planes (viz., those which are "beside" the sensi- ble planes, those contained in the mathematical solids, those which are "beside" these), four classes of lines, five of points. Now which of all these are to be the objects of the mathematical sciences? For it will surely not be said that it is the planes, lines, and points which are in the mo- tionless geometrical solid which are the objects of these sciences, since it is always the logically prior classes which are the objects of science.*

'i. e., purely geometrical, as distinguished from physical "bodies." The difference, according to Aristotle, between the objects of Mathematics and those of Physics is precisely that the former, though "inseparable from matter," are not capable of motion, the latter are "inseparable from matter but not incapable of motion." Metaphysics, E, 1026a 18.

2 The character of the reasoning will become clearer if we consider the simplest of the cases mentioned, that of the plane.

APPENDIX. 157

The same argument is applicable also to the case of numbers. For each class of points there will be a different

Aristotle contends that on a realist theory, like that of Plato, which regards the plane surfaces of Geometry not as mere logical abstrac- tions but as objective entities, there must be not only one but three classes of such entities, over and above the perceptible surfaces of physical bodies, viz.: (i) The single archetypal "Idea" of the plane, i. e., the entity to which we refer in giving the definition of the plane as such; (2) the entities which figure as constituents in the definition of the geometrical solid, e. g., as determined or bounded by four planes; (3) the infinitely numerous "mathematical planes" which appear in Geometry. It is of these last that "physical" plane surfaces are immediately "copies." Thus he arrives at the following series of entities as all implied in the Platonic theory:

3 classes of plane, viz.: (a) The plane as represented by its

definition.

(b) The plane as a boundary of solids

(c) "Mathematical" planes.

4 classes of line, viz. : (a) The line as represented by its

definition.

(b) The line as boundary, or rather

as intersection, of planes.

(c) The line as intersection of planes

which are boundaries of solids.

(d) "Mathematical" lines.

5 classes of point, viz. : (a) The point as represented by its

definition.

(b) The point as intersection of lines.

(c) The point as intersection of lines

which are intersections of planes.

(d) The point as intersection of lines

which are intersections of planes, which are boundaries of solids.

(e) "Mathematical" points.

I must leave the reader to decide whether the ingenuity of all this is not equalled by its perversity, merely observing that "by the same reasoning," there should be two and not, as Aristotle says, only one class of "solids" over and above "physical" solids.

«(C ^n«*w«'<|»^.: jyii#,»frJU,|£ J,»,>.^,.<<«it

158 ARISTOTLE ON HIS PREDECESSORS.

corresponding class of units/ and so again for each class of sensible objects, and again for each class of conceptual objects.^ Thus the numbers of classes of mathematical numbers will be infinite.

[Aristotle]^ De Lineis Insecabilibiis, 968a 9 14. (Text of Apelt in the Teubner series.) If there is an "Idea of Line," and the Idea is the archet\^e of all the objects which fall under the same concept, while the parts of an object are logically prior to the whole which they constitute, the "Ideal Line" must be indivisible. The same will be true of the "Ideal square" and "triangle," and all the other figures^ and universally of the "Ideal plane" and "Ideal solid;" for otherwise it would follow that there are things* which are logically prior to these entities.

ib. 969a 17-21. Those who construct indivisible lines among the Ideas make an assvunption viz., in postulat- ing Ideas of such objects which is perhaps of less ex- tended scope than that now under examination,* and in

1 Because a point is simply a " unit having position "

^ Because each object of sense or thought is a " unit," and also a "copy" of a simple "transcendent" unit.

^ The author of the essay, though certainly not Aristotle, is almost equally certainly one of his immediate disciples, possibly Theophrastus. See Apelt, Beitrage zur Geschichte der Griechischen Philosophic, p. 269.

* viz., the lines or planes into which the ' 'Ideal plane," or "solid," if divisible, may, according to the Platonists under discussion, be divided.

' The assumption under discussion is that there is a whole in- finitely numerous class of indivisible "mathematical" lines, or "infini- tesimal" Unes, which are, in fact, the entities commonly called points. "Aristotle's" objection, as Apelt {Loc. cit. p. 274, note 2) explains, is that you cannot infer the indivisibility of "mathematical" lines from the supposed indivisibility of the "Ideal Une;" on the

APPENDIX. 159

a sense they destroy the force of the very assumptions on which their proof rests. For such arguments are, in fact, subversive of the Ideas.

contrary, the only valid ground for calling the " Ideal line" indivisible would be your previous knowledge that "mathematical" Unes, as a class, are indivisibles. You have no right, on Platonic principles, to assume an Idea except when you already know of an existing class of coresponding individual things. There can be no idea corresponding to any class which is inconceivable. Hence, if it can be shown that all "mathematical" hnes are di\'isible, there can be no reason to postulate an "Idea" of the indivisible line.

INDEX OF PROPER NAMES.

Alcmaeon, 94-5.

Anaxagoras, 82-3, 86, 88, 106,

111-113, 124. Anaximenes, 82.

Cratylus, 100.

Democritus, 90, loi n. Diogenes, 82.

Empedocles, 82, 87-90, 106, iio-

III, 138, 139. Endoxus, 124.

Heraclitus, 82. Hermotimus, 86. Hesiod, 86, no. Hippasus, 82. Hippo, 82.

Leucippus, 90. Melissus, 96, 97.

Parmenides, 84, 86, 96, 97. Plato, 100-105, 106, 115, 116 ff. Polus, 68. Pythagoras, 95.

Pythagoreans, The, 91 ff, 98-99, loin., 103, 106, 113-116.

Simonides, 76. Socrates, 100, loi n.

Thales, 80-82. Xenophanes, 96, 97.

TITLE LIST OF OPEN COURT PUBLICATIONS ARRANGED ALPHABETICALLY BY AUTHORS

ANESAKI, M.

345- BUDDHIST AND CHRISTIAN GOSPELS, Being Gospel Paral- lels from Pali Texts. Now first compared from the originals by Albert J. Edmunds. Edited with parallels and notes from the Chinese Buddhist Triptaka by M. Anesaki $1.50 net.

BAYNE, JULIA TAFT. 323. HADLEY BALLADS. Julia Taft Bayne. 75c net.

BERKELEY, GEORGE.

307. A TREATISE CONCERNING THE PRINCIPLES OF HUMAN

KNOWLEDGE. George Berkeley. Cloth, 60c net. (3s. net.)

308. THREE DIALOGUES BETWEEN HYLAS AND PHILONOUS,

George Berkeley. Cloth, 6oc net. (3s. net.)

BINET, ALFRED.

201. THE PSYCHIC LIFE OF MICRO-ORGANISMS. Alfred Binet. 75c. (3s. 6d.)

270. THE PSYCHOLOGY OF REASONING. Alfred Binet. TransL by Adam Gowans Whyte. 750 net. (3s. 6d.)

296. ON DOUBLE CONSCIOUSNESS. Alfred Binet. Cloth, 50c net. (2s. 6d. net.)

BLOOMFIELD, MAURICE,

334- CERBERUS, THE DOG OF HADES. The History of an Idea. Prof. M. Bloomfield. Boards, 50c net. (2s. 6d. net.)

BONNEY, HONORABLE CHARLES CARROLL.

304. WORLD'S CONGRESS ADDRESSES, Delivered by the Presi- dent, the Hon. C. C. Bonney. Cloth, see net. (2s. 6d. net.)

BONNEY, FLORENCE PEORIA.

286. MEDITATIONS (Poems). Florence Peoria Bonney. Cloth, $1.00

nci.>

BUDGE, E .A. WALLIS.

325. THE GODS OF THE EGYPTIANS OR STUDIES IN EGYP- TIAN MYTHOLOGY. £. A. Wallis Budge. With plates and illustrations. 2 vols. Cloth, $20.00 net.

226. THE BOOK OF THE DEAD, a translation of the Chapters, Hymns, etc., of the Theban Recension. £. A. pyallis Budge. Illustrated. 3 vols. $3.75 per set net. Vols. VI, VII, VIII in the series of Books on Egyj)t and Chaldea.

X

tS'Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue."^

TITLE LIST

317. A HISTORY OF EGYPT, From the End of the Neolithic Period to the Death of Cleopatra VII, B. C. 30. E, A. Wallis Budge. Richly illustrated. 8 vols. Cloth, $10.00 net.

I. Egypt in the Neolithic and Archaic Period.

II. Egypt Under the Great Pyramid Builders.

III. Egypt Under the Amenembats and Hyksos.

IV. Egypt and her Asiatic Empire.

V. Egypt Under Rameses the Great.

VI. Egypt Under the Priest Kings and Tanites and Nubians.

VII. Egypt Under the Saites, Persians and Ptolemies.

VIII. Egypt Under the Ptolemies and Cleopatra VII.

CARUS, DR. PAUL. 204. FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS, the Method of PhUosophy as a Systematic Arrangement of Knowledge. Paul Carus. Cloth, $1.50. (7s. 6d.)

207. THE SOUL OF MAN, an Investigation of the Facts of Physio-

logical and Experimental Psychology. Paul Carus. Illustrated. Cloth, $1.50 net. (6s. net.)

208. PRIMER OF PHILOSOPHY. Paul Carus. Cloth, $1.00. (ss.)

210. MONISM AND MELIORISM, A Philosophical Essay on Causal ity and Ethics. Paul. Carus. Paper, 50c. (2s. 6d.)

213. (a) THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE TOOL. 10c. (6d.) (b) OUR NEED OF PHILOSOPHY, sc (3d.) (c) SCIENCE A RELIGIOUS REVELATION, sc . (3d.) Paul Carus.

290. THE SURD OF METAPHYSICS, An Inquiry into the Question Are thebe Things-in-themselves? Paul Carus. Cloth, $1.25 net. (ss. 6d. net.)

303. KANT AND SPENCER, A Study of the Fallacies of Agnosticism. Paul Carus. Cloth, soc net. (2s. 6d. net.)

312. KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYS- ICS. Edited by Paul Carus. Cloth, 75c net. (3s. 6d. net.)

215. THE GOSPEL OF BUDDHA, According to Old Records, told by

Paul Carus. Cloth, $1.00. (ss.)

254. BUDDHISM AND ITS CHRISTIAN CRITICS. Paul Carus. $1.25. (6s. 6d.)

261. GODWARD, A Record of Religious Progress. Paul Carus. 50c. (2S. 6d.)

278. THE HISTORY OF THE DEVIL AND THE IDEA OF EVIL, From the Earliest Times to the Present day. Paul Carus. Il- lustrated. $6.00. (30s.)

280. HISTORY OF THE CROSS. Paul Carus. (In preparation.)

321. THE AGE OF CHRIST. A Brief Review of the Conditions under which Christianity originated. Paul Carus. Paper, isc net. (lod.)

341. THE DHARMA, or the Religrion of Enlightenment, An Exposi- tion of Buddhism. Paul Carus. 15c. (gd.)

216. DAS EVANGELIUM BUDDHAS. A German translation of The

Gospel of Buddha. Cloth, $1.25. (s marks.)

SS'Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'

OPEN COURT PUBLICATIONS

2SS- LAO-TZE'S TAO TEH KING. Chinese English. With Introduc- tion, Transliteration and Notes by Paul Carus. $3.00 (15s.)

275- THE WORLD'S PARLIAMENT OF RELIGIONS AND THE RELIGIOUS PARLIAMENT EXTENSION, a Memorial Pub- lished by the Religious Parliament Extension Committee. Popu- lar edition. C. C. Bonney and Paul Carus.

205. HOMILIES OF SCIENCE. Paul Carus. Cloth, gilt top, $1 so

(7s. 6d.)

206. THE IDEA OF GOD. Paul Carus. Paper, 150. (gd.)

211. THE RELIGION OF SCIENCE. Paul Carus. Cloth, soc net

(2s. 6d.)

212. KARMA. A STORY OF BUDDHIST ETHICS. Paul Carus.

Illustrated by Kwason Suzuki. American edition, isc. (lod.)

268. THE ETHICAL PROBLEM. Three Lectures on Ethics as a Science. Paul Carus. Cloth, $1.25. (6s. 6d.)

28s. WHENCE AND WHITHER. An Inquiry into the Nature of the Soul, Its Origin and Its Destiny. Paul Carus. Cloth, 7sc net. (3s. 6d. net.)

291. NIRVANA, A STORY OF BUDDHIST PSYCHOLOGY, Paul Carus. Illustrated by Kwason Suzuki. Cloth, 6oc net. (3s. net.)

302. THE DAWN OF A NEW RELIGIOUS ERA, AND OTHER ESSAYS. Paul Carus. Cloth, soc net. (2s. 6d. net.)

209. TRUTH IN FICTION, Twelve Tales with a Moral. Paul Carus Cloth, 1.00 net. (ss.)

217. KARMA, A STORY OF EARLY BUDDHISM. Paul Carus. Illustrated. Crepe paper, tied in silk. 7sc. (3s. 6d.)

217G. KARMA, Eine buddhistische Erzahlung. Paul Carus. Illustrated 35c.

246. THE CROWN OF THORNS, a story of the Time of Christ

Paul Carus. Illustrated. Cloth 75c net. (3s. 6d. net.)

247. THE CHIEF'S DAUGHTER, a Legend of Niagara. Paul Carus.

Illustrated. Cloth, $1.00 net. (4s. 6d.)

267. SACRED TUNES FOR THE CONSECRATION OF LIFE Hymns of the Religion of Science. Paul Carus. 50c.

281. GREEK MYTHOLOGY. Paul Carus. In preparation.

282. EROS AND PSYCHE, A Fairy-Tale of Ancient Greece, Retold

after Apuleius, by Paul Carus. Illustrated. $1.50 net. (6s. net.)

295. THE NATURE OF THE STATE. Paul Carus. Cloth soc net. (2S. 6d. net)

224. GOETHE AND SCHILLER'S XENIONS. Selected and trans- lated by Paul Carus. Paper, 50c. (2s. 6d.)

243. FRIEDRICH SCHILLER, A Sketch of His Life and an Appre- ciation of His Poetry. Paul Carus. Bds. 7sc.

t^Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.^t

TITLE LIST

CLEMENT, ERNEST W.

331. THE JAPANESE FLORAL CALENDAR. E. W. Clement. Il- lustrated. Boards, 50c net. (2s. 6d. net.)

CONWAY, MONCURE DANIEL.

277. SOLOMON AND SOLOMONIC LITERATURE. M. D. Conway. Cloth, $1.50 net. (6s.)

COPE, E. D.

219. THE PRIMARY FACTORS OF ORGANIC EVOLUTION. E.

D. Cope, Ph. D. 2d ed. Illustrated. Cloth, $2.00 net. (10s.)

CORNILL, CARL HEINRICH.

220. THE PROPHETS OF ISRAEL, Popular Sketches from Old

Testament History. C. H. Cornill. Transl. by S. F. Corkran. $1.00 net. (ss.)

259. THE HISTORY OF THE PEOPLE OF ISRAEL From the Earliest Times to the Destruction of Jerusalem by the Romans. C.H. Cornill. TransL hy W. H. Carrutli. Cloth, $1.50 (7s. 6d.)

262. GESCHICHTE DES VOLKES ISRAEL. C. H. Cornill. Ge- bunden $2.00. (8 Mark.)

251. THE RISE OF THE PEOPLE OF ISRAEL. C. H. Cornill, in Epitomes of Three Sciences: Comparative Philology, Psy- chology AND Old Testament History. H. H. Oldenberg, J. Jastrow, C. H. Cornill. Colth, 50c net. (2s. 6d.)

CUMONT, FRANZ.

319. THE MYSTERIES OF MITHRA. Prof. Franz Cumont. Transl. by T.J. McCormack. Illus. Cloth, $1.50 net. (6s. 6d. net.)

DEDEKIND, RICHARD. 287. ESSAYS ON THE THEORY OF NUMBERS. I. Continuity AND Irrational Numbers. II. The Nature and Meaning of Numbers. if. Dedekind. Transl. by W. W. Beman. Cloth, 750 net. (3s. 6d. net.)

DELITZSCH, DR. FRIEDRICH.

293. BABEL AND BIBLE, A Lecture on the Significance of Assyrio- logical Research for Religion. Prof. F. Delitssch. Translated by T. J. McCormack. Illustrated. 50c net.

293a. BABEL AND BIBLE. Two Lectures on the Significance of Assyriological Research for Religion, Embodying the most im- portant Criticisms and the Author's Replies. Prof. F. Delitssch. Translated by T. J. McCormack and IV. H. Carruth. 75c net-

DE MORGAN, AUGUSTUS.

264. ON THE STUDY AND DIFFICULTIES OF MATHEMATICS. Augustus DeMorgan. Cloth, $1.25 net. (4s. 6d. net.)

271. ELEMENTARY ILLUSTRATIONS OF THE DIFFERENTIAL AND INTEGRAL CALCULUS. Augustus DeMorgan. Cloth, $1.00 net. (4s. 6d. net.)

t^Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'

OPEN COURT PUBLICATIONS

DESCARTES, RENE.

301. DISCOURSE ON THE METHOD OF RIGHTLY CONDUCT ING THE REASON AND SEEKING TRUTH IN THE SCI ENCES. Rene Descartes. Transl. by John Veitch. Cloth, 60c net. (3s. net.)

310. THE MEDITATIONS AND SELECTIONS FROM THE PRIN- CIPLES of Rene Descartes. Transl. hylohn Veitch. Cloth. 75c net. (3s. 6d. net.)

346. THE PRINCIPLES OF DESCARTES' PHILOSOPHY by Bene-

dictus de Spino:a. Introduction by Halbert Hains Britan, Ph. D. Cloth, 75c net, mailed 85c.

DE VRIES, HUGO. 332. SPECIES AND VARIETIES, THEIR ORIGIN BY MUTA- TION. Prof. Hugo de Vries. Edited by D. T. MacDougal. $5.00 net. (2 IS. net.)

EDMUNDS, ALBERT J.

218. HYMNS OF THE FAITH (DHAMMAPADA), being an Ancient Anthology Preserved in the Sacred Scriptures of the Buddhists. Transl. by Albert J. Edmunds. Cloth, $1.00 net. (4s. 6d. net.)

345. BUDDHIST AND CHRISTIAN GOSPELS, Being Gospel Paral- lels from Pali Texts. Now first compared from the originals by Albert J. Edmunds. Edited with parallels and notes from the Chinese Buddhist Triptaka by M. Anesaki $1.50 net.

EVANS, HENRY RIDGELY.

330. THE NAPOLEON MYTH. H. R. Evans. With "The Grand Erratum," by J. B. Peres, and Introduction by Paul Carus. Illustrated. Boards, 75c net. (3s. 6d. net.)

347. THE OLD AND THE NEW MAGIC. Henry R. Evans. Illustr.

Cloth, gilt top. $1.50 net, mailed $1.70.

FECHNER, GUSTAV THEODOR.

349. ON LIFE AFTER DEATH. Ctistav Theodor Fechner. Tr. from the German by Hugo Wernekke. Bds. 75c.

FINK, DR. CARL. 272. A BRIEF HISTORY OF MATHEMATICS. Dr. Karl Fink. Transl. from the German by IV. W. Beman and D. E. Smith. Cloth, $1.50 net. (ss. 6d. net.)

FREYTAG, GUSTAV.

248. MARTIN LUTHER. Custav Freytag. Transl. by H. £. O. Heine- maim. Illustrated. Cloth, $1.00 net. (5s.)

221. THE LOST MANUSCRIPT. A Novel. Gustav Freytag. Two

vols. Cloth, $4.00. (21s.) 221a. THE SAME. One vol. $1.00. (5s.)

GARBE, RICHARD.

223. THE PHILOSOPHY OF ANCIENT INDIA. Prof. R. Garbe. Cloth, 50c net. (2S. 6d. net.)

222. THE REDEMPTION OF THE BR.MIMAN. A novel. Richard

Garbe. Cloth, 75c. (3s. 6d.)

SSS'Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'SSi

TITLE LIST

GOODWIN. REV. T. A.

22S. LOVERS THREE THOUSAND YEARS AGO, as indicated by The Song of Solomon. Rev. T. A. Goodwin, soc net. (2s. 6d.)

GUNKEL, HERMANN.

227. THE LEGENDS OF GENESIS. Prof. H. Gunkel. Transl. by

Prof. W. H. Carruth. Cloth, $1.00 net. (4s. 6d. net.)

HAUPT, PAUL. 202. BIBLICAL LOVE - DITTIES, A CRITICAL INTERPRETA- TION AND TRANSLATION OF THE SONG OF SOLO- MON. Prof. Paul Haupt. Paper, sc. (3d.)

HERING, PROF. EWALD. 298. ON MEMORY AND THE SPECIFIC ENERGIES OF THE NERVOUS SYSTEM. E. Hering. CI. soc net. (2s. 6d. net.)

HILBERT, DAVID. 289. THE FOUNDATIONS OF GEOMETRY. Prof. David Hilbert. Transl. by £. /. Townsend. Cloth, $1.00 net. (4s. 6d. net.)

HOLYOAKE, GEORGE JACOB.

228. ENGLISH SECULARISM, A Confession of Belief. G. J. Holy-

oake. Cloth, soc net.

HUG, M.

244. TRAVELS IN TARTARY, THIBET AND CHINA, During the Years 1844-S-6. M. Hue. Transl. by W. Haslitt. Illustrated. One volume. $1.25 net. (ss. net.)

z6o. THE SAME. Two volumes. $2.00. (los net.)

HUEPPE, DR. FERDINAND.

2S7. THE PRINCIPLES OF BACTERIOLOGY. Ferdinand Hueppe. Transl. by Dr. E. O. Jordan. $1.75 net. (9s.)

HUME, DAVID.

305. AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING HUMAN UNDERSTANDING.

David Hume. Cloth, 6oc net. (3s. net.)

306. AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING THE PRINCIPLES OF MOR-

ALS. David Hume. Cloth, 60c net. (3s. net.)

HUTCHINSON, WOODS. 2s6. THE GOSPEL ACCORDING TO DARWIN. Woods Hutchinson. Cloth, $1.50. (6s.)

HYLAN, JOHN P. 309. PUBLIC WORSHIP, A STUDY IN THE PSYCHOLOGY OF RELIGION. /. P. Hylan. Cloth, 6oc net. (3s. net.)

INGRAHAM, ANDREW.

322. SWAIN SCHOOL LECTURES. Andrew Ingraham. $1.00 net.

KHEIRALLA, GEORGE IBRAHIM. 326. BEHA 'U'LLAH (THE GLORY OF GOD). Ibrahim George Kheiralla, assisted by Howard MacNutt. $3.00.

SS'Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'^ii

OPEN COURT PUBLICATIONS

LAGRANGE, JOSEPH LOUIS.

2s8 LECTURES ON ELEMENTARY MATHEMATICS. 7. L. La- grange. Transl. by T. J. McCormack. Cloth, $i.oo net. (4s. 6d. net.)

LEIBNIZ, G. W

1.1 1 LEIBNIZ: DISCOURSE ON METAPHYSICS, CORRESPOND- ENCE WITH ARNAULD and MONADOLOGY. Dr. George R. Montgomery. Cloth, 75c net. (3s. 6d. net.)

LEVY-BRUHL, LUCIEN. 273. HISTORY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY IN FRANCE. Lucitm Levy-Bruhl. With portraits. $3.00 net. (12s. net.)

LOYSON, EMILIE HYACINTHE.

338. TO JERUSALEM THROUGH THE LANDS OF ISLAM. EmUie

Hyacinthe Loysoti. Illustrated. Cloth, $2.50.

MACH, ERNST.

229. THE SCIENCE OF MECHANICS, A Critical and Historical Ac-

count of its Development. Prof. Ernst Mach. Transl. by T. J. McCormack. Illustrated. $2.00 net. (9s. 6d. net.)

230. POPULAR SCIENTIFIC LECTURES. Professor Ernst Mach.

Transl. by T. J. McCormack. Illust. $1.50 net. (7s. 6d. net.)

2S0. CONTRIBUTIONS TO THE ANALYSIS OF THE SENSA- TIONS. Prof. Ernst Mach. Transl. by C. M, IVxlUams. $1.25 net. (6s. 6d.)

MILLS, LAWRENCE H.

318. ZARATHUSHTRIAN GATHAS, in Meter and Rhythm. Prof. Lawrence H. Mills. Cloth, $2.00.

339. ZARATHUSHTRA AND THE GREEKS, a Treatise upon the

Antiquities of the Avcsta with Special Reference to the Logos- Conception. Prof. Lawrence H. Mills. Cloth, $2.00 net.

MUELLER, F. MAX.

231. THREE INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON THE SCIENCE

OF THOUGHT. F. Max Miiller. With a correspondence on Thought without words between F. Max Miiller and Francis Galton, the Duke of Argyll, G. J. Romanes and Others. Cloth, 75c. (3s. 6d.)

232. THREE LECTURES ON THE SCIENCE OF LANGUAGE.

With a supplement. My Predecessors. F. Max Mullet. Cloth, 75c. (3s. 6d.)

NAEGELI, CARL VON. 300. A MECHANICO-PHYSIOLOGICAL THEORY OF ORGANIC EVOLUTION. Carl von Ndgeli. Cloth, 50c net. (2s. 6d. net)

NOIRE, LUDWIG. 297. ON THE ORIGIN OF LANGUAGE, and THE LOGOS THE- ORY. Ludwig Noire. Cloth, see net. (2s. 6d. net.)

Sa'Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'^k

TITLE LIST

OLDENBERG, PROF. H.

233. ANCIENT INDIA, Its Language and Religions. Prof. H. Olden-

berg. Cloth, 50c net. (2s. 6d.)

POWELL, J. W.

265. TRUTH AND ERROR, or the Science of Intellection. /. W.

Powell. $1.75. (7s. 6d.)

315. JOHN WESLEY POWELL: A Memorial to an American Ex- plorer and Scholar. Mrs. M. D. Lincoln, G. K. Gilbert, M. Baker and Paul Carus. Edited by G. K. Gilbert. Paper, soc net.

RADAU, DR. HUGO.

294. THE CREATION STORY OF GENESIS I. A Sumerian Theog- ony and Cosmogony. H. Radau. Bds., 7sc net. (3s. 6d. net.)

RIBOT, TH.

234. THE PSYCHOLOGY OF ATTENTION. Th. Ribot. Cloth, 730.

(3S. 6d.) 23s. THE DISEASES OF PERSONALITY. Th. Ribot. Cloth, 7Sc. (3S. 6d.)

236. THE DISEASES OF THE WILL. Th. Ribot. Transl. by Mer-

win-Marie Snell. Cloth, 75c. (3s. 6d.) 279. THE EVOLUTION OF GENERAL IDEAS. Th. Ribot. Transl. by Frances A. Welby. Cloth, $1.25. (ss.)

ROMANES, GEORGE JOHN.

237. DARWIN AND AFTER DARWIN, An Exposition of the Dar-

winian Theory and a Discussion of Post-Darwinian Questions. Oeorge John Romanes. Three volumes. $4.00 net.

238. Part I. The Darwinian Theory. Cloth, $2.00.

239. Part II. Post-Darwinian Questions: Heredity and Utility. Cloth, $1.50.

252. Part III. Post-Darwinian Questions: Isolation and Physiological Selection. Cloth, $1.00.

240. AN EXAMINATION OF WEISMANNISM. George John Ro- manes. Cloth, $1.00 net.

214. A CANDID EXAMINATION OF THEISM. Physicus (the late G. J. Romanes). Cloth, $2.00.

242. THOUGHTS ON RELIGION. The late G. J. Romanes. Edited by Charles Gore. Cloth, $1.25 net.

ROW, T. SUNDARA.

284. GEOMETRIC EXERCISES IN PAPER FOLDING. T. Sundara Row. Edited by IV. W. Beman, and D. E. Smith. Illustrated. Cloth, $1.00 net. (4s. 6d. net.)

RUTH, J. A.

329. WHAT IS THE BIBLE? /. A. Ruth. 75c net. (3s. 6d. net.)

SCHUBERT, HERMANN.

266. MATHEMATICAL ESSAYS AND RECREATIONS. Prof. Her-

mann Schubert. Transl. by T. J. McCormack. Cloth, 750 net. (3s. 6d. net.)

l^rSend for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'^jk

OPEN COURT PUBLICATIONS

SHUTE, D. KERFOOT. 276. A FIRST BOOK IN ORGANIC EVOLUTION. D. Kerfoot Shute. Cloth, $2.00 net. (73. 6d. net.)

STANLEY, HIRAM M. 274. PSYCHOLOGY FOR BEGINNERS. An Outline Sketch. Hiram M. Stanley. Boards, 40c net. (2s.)

ST. ANSELIM. 324. ST. ANSELM: PROSLOGIUM; MONOLOGIUM; AN APPEN- DIX IN BEHALF OF THE FOOL, by Gaunilon; and CUR DEUS HOMO. Transl. by S. N. Deane. Cloth, $1.00 net.

STARR. FREDERICK.

327. READINGS FROM MODERN MEXICAN AUTHORS. Fred-

erick Starr. $1.25 net. (5s. 6d. net.)

328. THE AINU GROUP AT THE SAINT LOUIS EXPOSITION.

Frederick Starr. Illustrated. Boards, 75c net. (3s. 6d. net.)

STRODE, MURIEL.

333. MY LITTLE BOOK OF PRAYER. Muriel Strode. Boards, 50c-

net. (2S. 6d. net.) 333a. THE SAME. Cloth, $1.00 net. (4s. 6d. net.)

SUZUKI, TEITARO. 283. ACVAGHOSHA'S DISCOURSE ON THE AWAKENING OF FAITH IN THE MAHAYANA. Translated by Teitaro Su- zuki. Cloth, $1.23 net. (5s. net.)

TOLSTOY, COUNT LEO.

348. CHRISTIANITY AND PATRIOTISM with Pertinent Extracts from other Essays. Count Leo Tolstoy. Trans, by Paul Borger and others. Paper, 35c net, mailed 40c.

TOPINARD, PAUL. 260. SCIENCE AND FAITH, OR MAN AS AN ANIMAL, AND MAN AS A MEMBER OF SOCIETY, with a DISCUSSION OF ANIMAL SOCIETIES, by Paul Topinard. Transl. by T. J. McCormack. $1.50 net. (6s. 6d. net.)

TRUMBULL, M. M.

243. WHEELBARROW, Articles and Discussions on the Laror Question, including the Controversy with Mr. Lyman J. Gage on the Ethics of the Board of Trade; and also the Controversy with Hugh O. Pentecost and Others, on the Single Tax Ques- tion. Cloth, $1.00. (ss.)

245. THE FREE TRADE STRUGGLE IN ENGLAND. M. M. Trum- bull. Cloth, 75c. (3s. 6d.)

WAGNER, RICHARD.

249. A PILGRIMAGE TO BEETHOVEN. A Novel by Richard Wag- ner. Transl. by O. W. Weyer. Boards, 50c net. (2s. 6d.)

WEISMANN, AUGUST.

299. ON GERMINAL SELECTION, as a Source of definite Variation. August Weismann. Transl. by T. J. McCormack. Cloth, 6oc

net. ("35. net.)

XS'Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'^i

10 TITLE LIST

WITHERS, JOHN WILLIAM.

335. EUCLID'S PARALLEL POSTULATE; Its Nature, Validity AND Place in Geometrical Systems. /. W. Withers, Ph. D., Cloth, $1.25 net. (4s. 6d. net.)

YAMADA, KEICHYU.

265. SCENES FROM THE LIFE OF BUDDHA. Reproduced from paintings by Prof. Keichyu Yamada... $2.50 net. dss.)

316. THE TEMPLES OF THE ORIENT AND THEIR MESSAGE IN THE LIGHT OF HOLY SCRIPTURE, Dante's Vision, and Bunyan's Allegory. By the author of "Clear Round!" "Things Touching the King," etc. $4.00

PORTRAITS AND ILLUSTRATIONS

332a. FRAMING PORTRAIT OF HUGO BE VRIES. Platino finish. 10X12", unmounted. Postpaid, $1.00. (4s. 6d. net.)

336. PORTFOLIO OF BUDDHIST ART. A collection of illustra- tions of Buddhism, Historical and Modern in portfolio, see net. (2s. 6d. net.)

202. PHILOSOPHICAL AND PSYCHOLOGICAL PORTRAIT SE- RIES. 68 portraits on plate paper, $7.50 (3Ss.) per set.

202a. PHILOSOPHICAL PORTRAIT SERIES. 43 portraits on plate paper, $6.25 (30s.) Single portraits, on plate paper, 25c. (is. 6d.)

202b. PSYCHOLOGICAL PORTRAIT SERIES. 25 portraits on Japa- nese paper, $5.00 (24s.) per set; plate paper, $3.75 (i8s.) per set. Single portraits, Japanese paper, 50c (2s. 6d.); single portraits, on plate paper, 25c (is. 6d.)

SMITH, PROF. DAVID EUGENE.

202C. PORTRAITS OF MATHEMATICIANS. Edited by Prof. D. E. Smith. 12 portraits on Imp. Jap. Vellum, $s-oo; 12 portraits on Am. plate paper, $3.00.

THE RELIGION OF SCIENCE LIBRARY

THE RELIGION OF SCIENCE. Paul Carus. 25c, mailed 30c. (is. 6d.)

THREE INTRODUCTORY LECTURES ON THE SCIENCE OF THOUGHT. F. Max Miiller. With a correspondence on "Thought Without Words" between F. Max Miiller and Francis Galton, the Duke of Argyll, George J. Romanes and others. 2SC, mailed 29c. (is. 6d.)

THREE LECTURES ON THE SCIENCE OF LANGUAGE. With My Predecessors. F. Max Mailer. 25c, mailed 29c. (is. 6d.)

THE DISEASES OF PERSONALITY. Prof. Th. Ribot. 2sc, mailed 29c. (is. 6d.)

tS'Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'^ii

OPEN COURT PUBLICATIONS

THE PSYCHOLOGY OF ATTENTION. Prof. Th. Ribot. 2sc, mailed 29c. (is. 6d.)

THE PSYCHIC LIFE OF MICRO-ORGANISMS. A Study in Experimental Psychology. Alfred Binet. 250, mailed 29c. (is. 6d.)

Paul Carus. 150, mailed 18c.

7. THE NATURE OF THE STATE.

(9d.)

8. ON DOUBLE CONSCIOUSNESS. Experimental Psychological

Studies. Alfred Binet. isc mailed i8c. (9d.)

9. FUNDAMENTAL PROBLEMS. The Method of Philosophy as

a Systematic Arrangement of Knowledge. Paul Carus. soc, mailed 60c. (2s. 6d.)

10. DISEASES OF THE WILL. Prof. Th. Ribot. Transl. by Mer- win-Marie Snell. 25c, mailed 29c. (is. 6d.)

i:. ON THE ORIGIN OF LANGUAGE and the Logos Theory. L. Noire. 15c, mailed i8c. (is. 6d.)

12. THE FREE TRADE STRUGGLE IN ENGLAND. M. M. Trum-

bull. 25c, mailed 31c. (is. 6d.)

13. WHEELBARROW, ARTICLES AND DISCUSSIONS ON THE

LABOR QUESTION, including the Controversy with Mr. Ly- man J. Gage on the Ethics of the Board of Trade; and also the Controversy with Mr. Hugh O. Pentecost, and others, on the Single Tax Question. 3sc, mailed 43c. (2s.)

14. THE GOSPEL OF BUDDHA, According to Old Records told by

Paul Carus. 35c, mailed 42c. (2s.)

15. PRIMER OF

(is. 6d.)

16. ON MEMORY AND THE SPECIFIC ENERGIES OF THE

NERVOUS SYSTEM. Prof. E. Bering. 15c, mailed iSc. (9d.)

17. THE REDEMPTION OF THE BRAHMAN. A Novel. Richard

Garbe. 25c, mailed 28c. (is. 6d.)

18. AN EXAMINATION OF WEISMANNISM. C. J. Romanes.

3SC, mailed 41c. (2s.)

19. ON GERMINAL SELECTION AS A SOURCE OF DEFINITE

VARIATION. August IVeismann. Transl. by T. J. McCor- mack. 25c, mailed 28c. (is. 6d.)

20. LOVERS THREE THOUSAND YEARS AGO as Indicated by

The Song of Solomon. Rev. T. A. Goodwin, isc, mailed 18c. (9d.)

21. POPULAR SCIENTIFIC LECTURES. Professor Ernst Mach.

Transl. by T. J. McCormack. soc, mailed 60c. (2s. 6d.)

22. ANCIENT INDIA, ITS LANGUAGE AND RELIGIONS. Prof.

PHILOSOPHY. Paul Carus. 250, mailed 32c.

THE PROPHETS OF ISRAEL. Popular Sketches from Old Testament History. Prof. C. H. Cornill. Transl. by 5. F. Corkran. 2SC, mailed 30c. (is. 6d.)

SS'Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'^t

12 TITLE LIST

24. HOMILIES OF SCIENCE. Paul Carus. 35c, mailed 43c. (2s.)

25. THOUGHTS ON RELIGION. The late G. J. Romanes. Edited

by Charles Gore. 50c, mailed 550. (2s. 6d.)

26. THE PHILOSOPHY OF ANCIENT INDIA. Prof. R. Garbe.

25c, mailed 28c. (is. 6d.)

27. MARTIN LUTHER. Gustav Freytag. Transl. by H. E. O.

Heinemann. 25c, mailed 30c. (is. 6d.)

28. ENGLISH SECULARISM. A Confession of Belief. George J.

Holyoake. 25c, mailed 30c. (is. 6d.)

29. ON ORTHOGENESIS AND THE IMPORTANCE OF NATU-

RAL SELECTION IN SPECIES-FORMATION. Prof. Th. Eimer. Transl. by T. J. McCormack. 250, mailed 30. (is. 6d.)

30. CHINESE PHILOSOPHY. An Exposition of the Main Char-

acteristic Features of Chinese Thought. Dr. Paul Carus. 2Sc, mailed 30c. (is. 6d.)

31. THE LOST MANUSCRIPT. A Novel. Gustav Freytag. One

volume. 60c, mailed 80c. (3s.)

32. A MECHANICO-PHYSIOLOGICAL THEORY OF ORGANIC

EVOLUTION. Carl von Nageli. isc, mailed i8c. (pd.)

33. CHINESE FICTION. Rev. G. T. Candlin. Illustrated. 150,

mailed i8c. (gd.)

34. MATHEMATICAL ESSAYS AND RECREATIONS. Prof. H.

Schubert. Tr. by T. J. McCormack. 2sc, mailed 30c. (is. 6d.)

35. THE ETHICAL PROBLEM. Three Lectures on Ethics as a

Science. Paul Carus. 50c, mailed 6oc. (2s. 6d.)

36. BUDDHISM AND ITS CHRISTIAN CRITICS. Paul Carus.

50c, mailed 58c. (2s. 6d.)

37. PSYCHOLOGY FOR BEGINNERS. An Outline Sketch. Hiram

M. Stanley. 20c, mailed 23c. (is.)

38. DISCOURSE ON THE METHOD OF RIGHTLY CONDUCT-

ING THE REASON, AND SEEKING TRUTH IN THE SCIENCES. Rene Descartes. Transl. by Prof. John Veitch. 2SC, mailed 29c. (is. 6d.)

39. THE DAWN OF A NEW RELIGIOUS ERA and other Essays.

Paul Carus. 15c, mailed i8c. (gd.)

40. KANT AND SPENCER, a Study of the Fallacies of Agnosti-

cism. Paul Carus. 20c, mailed 25c. (is.)

41. THE SOUL OF MAN, an Investigation of the Facts of Physio

logical and Experimental Psychology. Paul Carus. 75c, mailed 85c. (3s. 6d.)

42. WORLD'S CONGRESS ADDRESSES, Delivered by the Presi-

dent, the Hon. C. C. Bonney. 15c, mailed 20c. (gd.)

43. THE GOSPEL ACCORDING TO DARWIN. Woods Hutchinson.

Soc, mailed 57c. (2s. 6d.)

44. WHENCE AND WHITHER. The Nature of the Soul, Its

Origin and Destiny. Paul Carus. 25c, mailed 32c. (is. 6d.)

SWSend for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'

OPEN COURT PUBLICATIONS

45. AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING HUMAN UNDERSTANDING.

David Hume. 250, mailed 31c. (is. 6d.)

46. AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING THE PRINCIPLES OF MOR

ALS. David Hume. 25c, mailed 31c. (is. 6d.)

47. THE PSYCHOLOGY OF REASONING, Based on Experimental

Researches in Hypnotism. Alfred Binet. Transl. by Adam Gowans Whyte. 2$c, mailed 31c. (is. 6d.)

48. A TREATISE CONCERNING THE PRINCIPLES OF HUMAN

KNOWLEDGE. George Berkeley. 25c, mailed 31c. (is. 6d.)

49. THREE DIALOGUES BETWEEN HYLAS AND PHILONOUS.

George Berkeley. 25c, mailed 30c. (is. 6d.)

50. PUBLIC WORSHIP, A STUDY IN THE PSYCHOLOGY OF

RELIGION. John P. Hylan. 25c, mailed 29c. (is. 6d.)

51. THE MEDITATIONS AND SELECTIONS FROM THE PRIN-

CIPLES of Reyie Descartes. Transl. by Prof. John Veitch. 3SC, mailed 42c. (2s.)

52. LEIBNIZ: DISCOURSE ON METAPHYSICS, CORRESPOND-

ENCE WITH ARNAULD and MONADOLOGY, with an In- troduction by Paul Janet. Transl. by Dr. G. R. Montgomery. 50C, mailed 58c. (2s. 6d.)

53. KANT'S PROLEGOMENA to any Future Metaphysics. Edited

by Dr. Paul Carus. 50c, mailed 59c. (2s. 6d.)

S4 ST. ANSELM: PROSLOGIUM; MONOLOGIUM; AN APPEN DIX ON BEHALF OF THE FOOL, by Gaunilon; and CUR DEUS HOMO. Tr. by S. N. Deane. 50c, mailed 60c. (2s. 6d.)

55. THE CANON OF REASON AND VIRTUE (Lao-Tze's Tag Teh

King). Translated from the Chinese by Paul Carus. 25c, mailed 28c. (is. 6d.)

56. ANTS AND SOME OTHER INSECTS, an Inquiry into the

Psychic Powers of these Animals, with an Appendix on the Peculiarities of Their Olfactory Sense. Dr. August Forel. Transl. by Prof. W. M. Wheeler. 50c, mailed 53c. (2s. 6d.)

57. THE METAPHYSICAL SYSTEM OF HOBBES, as contained

in twelve chapters from his "Elements of Philosophy Concern- ing Body," and in briefer Extracts from his "Human Nature"' and "Leviathan," selected by Mary Whiten Calkins. 40c, mailed 47c. (2s.)

58. LOCKE'S ESSAYS CONCERNING HUMAN UNDERSTAND-

ING. Books II and IV (with omissions). Selected by Mary Whiton Calkins, soc, mailed 6oc. (2s. 6d.)

59. THE PRINCIPLES OF DESCARTES' PHILOSOPHY. Bene-

dictus de Spinoza. Introduction by Halbgrt Hains Britan, Ph. D. Paper, 3Sc net, mailed 42c.

THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING CO. 1322 Wabash Avenue, Chicago

London : Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., Ltd.

SS'Send for Complete Illustrated Catalogue.'^ii

THE OPEN COOei

ex H HUrr.,

An Illustrated Monthly Magazine

Devoted to the Science of Religion, The Religion of Science and the Extension of The Religious Parliament Idea

THE OPEN COURT is a popular magazine discussing the deepest questions of life. It offers the maturest thought in the domains of Religion, Philosophy, Psychology, Evo- lution and kindred subjects.

THE OPEN COURT contains articles on the recent discoveries of Babylonian and Egyptian excavations, on Old Testament Research, the Religion of the American Indians, Chinese culture, Brahmanism, Buddhism, Mithraism in short anything that will throw light on the development of religion and especially on Christianity.

THE OPEN COURT investigates the problems of God and Soul, of life and death and immortality, of conscience, duty, and the nature of morals, the ethics of political and social life briefly all that will explain the bottom facts of Religion and their practical significance. The illustrations though artistic are instructive and frequently reproduce rare historical pictures.

50 Cents Per Copy

THE MONIST

$2.00 Per Year

A Quarterly Magazine

Devoted to the Philosophy of Science. Each copy contains 160 pages; original articles, correspondence from foreign countries, discussions, and book reviews

The Monist Advocates the Philosophy of Science

Which is an application of the scientific method to philosophy. The old philosophical systems were mere air-castles (constructions of abstract theories), built in the realm of pure thought. The Philosophy of Science is a systematization of positive facts; it takes experience as its foundation, and uses the systematized formal relations of experience (mathe- matics, logic, etc.) as its method. It is oppo.sed on the one hand to the dogmatism of groundless a priori assumptions, and on the other hand, to the scepticism of negation which finds expression in the agnostic tendencies of to-day.

Monism Means a Unitary World - Conception

There may be different aspects and even contrasts, diverse views and opposite standpoints, but there can never be contradiction in truth. Monism is not a one-substance theory, be it materialistic or spiritual- istic or agnostic; it means simply and solely con- sistency. All truths form one consistent system, and any dualism of irreconcilable statements indicates that there is a problem to be solved; there must be fault somewhere either in our reasoning or in our knowledge of facts. Science always implies Monism, i. e., a unitary world-conception.

Illustrated Catalogue and Sample Copies Free.

The Open Court Publishing Co.

1322-1328 Wabash Avenue, Chicago, Illinois

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY Los Angeles

This book is DUE on the last date stamped below.

OJ 757T., . '.&"?

URL

APR

B*

^l, APR 7

mECD LD-UM

•JUN 18 - JUN 1 8 1986

Form TJ|ja|^ie^i39|QR7

igseMAR 1 3 1988

3 1158 00295 4831

AA 000 815 667 i

■v=^^/

mm

\-V*'"U

X v'y /

.'7A'as-

?;<;y.

V^S'Ti'WK

,\. ffi^