= 00 •CO CO UNIV. OF TORONTO LIBRARY ! SYSTEM OF LOGIC RATIOCINATIVE AND INDUCTIVE VOL. I. SYSTEM OF LOGIC RATIOCINATIVE AND INDUCTIVE BEING A CONNECTED VIEW OF THE PRINCIPLES OF EVIDENCE AND THE METHODS OF SCIENTIFIC INVESTIGATION BY IN TWO VOLUMES VOL. I. f SEVENTH EDITION LONDON : LONGMANS, GREEN, READER, AND DYER MDCCCLXVIII 6 i PEEFACE TO THE FIEST EDITION. THIS book makes no pretence of giving to the world a new theory of the intellectual operations. Its claim to attention, if it possess any, is grounded on the fact that it is an attempt not to supersede, but to embody and systematize, the best ideas which have been either promulgated on its subject by speculative writers, or conformed to by accurate thinkers in their scientific inquiries. To cement together the detached fragments of a subject, never yet treated as a whole ; to harmonize the true portions of discordant theories, by supplying the links of thought necessary to connect them, and by disentangling them from the errors with which they are always more or less interwoven ; must necessarily require a considerable amount of original speculation. To other originality than this, the pre sent work lays no claim. In the existing state of the cultivation of the sciences, there would be a very strong presumption against any one who should imagine that he had effected a revolution in the theory of the investigation of truth, or added any fundamentally new process to the practice of it. The improvement which remains to be effected in the methods of philosophizing (and the author be lieves that they have much need of improvement) can only consist in performing, more systematically b 3 VI PREFACE. and accurately, operations witli which, at least in their elementary form, the human intellect in some one or other of its employments is already familiar. In the portion of the work which treats of Katio- cination, the author has not deemed it necessary to enter into technical details which may be obtained in so perfect a shape from the existing treatises on what is termed the Logic of the Schools. In the contempt entertained by many modern philosophers for the syllogistic art, it will be seen that he by no means participates; though the scientific theory on which its defence is usually rested appears to him erro neous : and the view which he has suggested of the nature and functions of the Syllogism may, perhaps, afford the means of conciliating the principles of the art with as much as is well grounded in the doctrines and objections of its assailants. The same abstinence from details could not be observed in the First Book, on Names and Proposi tions; because many useful principles and distinc tions which were contained in the old Logic, have been gradually omitted from the writings of its later teachers; and it appeared desirable both to revive these, and to reform and rationalize the philosophical foundation on which they stood. The earlier chap ters of this preliminary Book will consequently appear, to some readers, needlessly elementary and scholastic. But those who know in what darkness the nature of our knowledge, and of the processes by which it is obtained, is often involved by a confused apprehension of the import of the different classes of Words and Assertions, will not regard these discus sions as either frivolous, or irrelevant to the topics considered in the later Books. PREFACE. Vll On the subject of Induction, the task to be per formed was that of generalizing the modes of investi gating truth and estimating evidence, by which so many important and recondite laws of nature have, in the various sciences, been aggregated to the stock of human knowledge. That this is not a task free from difficulty may be presumed from the fact, that even at a very recent period, eminent writers (among whom it is sufficient to name Archbishop Whately, and the author of a celebrated article on Bacon in the Edinburgh Review] have not scrupled to pro nounce it impossible.* The author has endeavoured to combat their theory in the manner in which Diogenes confuted the sceptical reasonings against the possibility of motion; remembering that Dio genes' argument would have been equally conclusive, though his individual perambulations might not have extended beyond the circuit of his own tub. Whatever may be the value of what the author has succeeded in effecting on this branch of his sub ject, it is a duty to acknowledge that for much of it * In the later editions of Archbishop Whately 's Logic, he states his meaning to be, not that " rules" for the ascertainment of truths by inductive investigation cannot be laid down, or that they may not be " of eminent service," but that they " must always be com paratively vague and general, and incapable of being built up into a regular demonstrative theory like that of the Syllogism." (Book iv. ch. iv. § 3.) And he observes, that to devise a system for this purpose, capable of being " brought into a scientific form," would be an achievement which " he must be more sanguine than scien tific who expects." (Book iv. ch. ii. § 4.) To effect this, however, being the express object of the portion of the present work which treats of Induction, the words in the text are no overstatement of the difference of opinion between Archbishop Whately and me on the subject. Vlll PREFACE. he has been indebted to several important treatises, partly historical and partly philosophical, on the generalities and processes of physical science, which have been published within the last few years. To these treatises, and to their authors, he has endea voured to do justice in the body of the work. But as with one of these writers, Dr. Whewell, he has occasion frequently to express differences of opinion, it is more particularly incumbent on him in this place to declare, that without the aid derived from the facts and ideas contained in that gentleman's History of the Inductive (Sciences, the corresponding portion of this work would probably not have been written. The concluding Book is an attempt to contribute towards the solution of a question, which the decay of old opinions, and the agitation that disturbs Euro pean society to its inmost depths, render as impor tant in the present day to the practical interests of human life, as it must at all times be to the com pleteness of our speculative knowledge : viz. Whether moral and social phenomena are really exceptions to the general certainty and uniformity of the course of nature ; and how far the methods, by which so many of the laws of the physical world have been numbered among truths irrevocably acquired and universally assented to, can be made instrumental to the forma tion of a similar body of received doctrine in moral and political science. PEEFACE TO THE THIED AND FODETH EDITIONS, SEVERAL criticisms, of a more or less controversial character, on this work, have appeared since the pub lication of the second edition ; and Dr. Whewell has lately published a reply to those parts of it in which some of his opinions were controverted.* I have carefully reconsidered all the points on which my conclusions have been assailed. But I have not to announce a change of opinion on any matter of importance. Such minor oversights as have been detected, either by myself or by my critics, I have, in general silently, corrected: but it is not to be inferred that I agree with the objec tions which have been made to a passage, in every instance in which I have altered or cancelled it. I have often done so, merely that it might not remain a stumbling-block, when the amount of discussion necessary to place the matter in its true light would have exceeded what was suitable to the occasion. To several of the arguments which have been urged against me, I have thought it useful to reply with some degree of minuteness ; not from any taste * Now forming a chapter in his volume on The Philosophy of Discovery. PREFACE. for controversy, but because the opportunity was favourable for placing my own conclusions, and the grounds of them, more clearly and completely before the reader. Truth, on these subjects, is militant, and can only establish itself by means of conflict. The most opposite opinions can make a plausible show of evidence while each has the statement of its own case ; and it is only possible to ascertain which of them is in the right, after hearing and comparing what each can say against the other, and what the other can urge in its defence. Even the criticisms from which I most dissent have been of great service to me, by showing in what places the exposition most needed to be improved, or the argument strengthened. And I should have been well pleased if the book had undergone a much greater amount of attack ; as in that case I should probably have been enabled to improve it still more than I believe I have now done. In the subsequent editions, the attempt to improve the work lay additions and corrections, suggested by criticism or by thought, has been continued. In the present (seventh) edition, a few further corrections have been made, but no material additions. CONTENTS OP THE FIRST VOLUME. INTRODUCTION. PAGB § 1. A definition at the commencement of a subject must be provisional ...... 1 2. Is logic the art and science of reasoning ? . . .2 3. Or the art and science of the pursuit of truth ? .3 4. Logic is concerned with inferences, not with intuitive truths 5 5. Eelation of logic to the other sciences . . .8 6. Its utility, how shown . . . . .10 7. Definition of logic stated and illustrated . . .11 BOOK I. OF NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. CHAPTEB I. Of the Necessity of commencing with an Analysis of Language. § 1. Theory of names, why a necessary part of logic . . 17 2. First step in the analysis of Propositions . . .18 3. Names must be studied before Things . . .21 CHAPTER II. Of Names. § 1. Names are names of things, not of our ideas . . 23 2. Words which are not names, but parts of names . . 24 3. General and Singular names . . . .26 4. Concrete and Abstract . . . . .29 5. Connotative and Non-connotative . . . .31 6. Positive and Negative . . . . .42 7. Relative and Absolute . . . . .44 8. Univocal and ^Equivocal . . . .47 CONTENTS. CHAPTER III. Of the Things denoted ly Names. PAGE § 1. Necessity of an enumeration of Nameable Things. The Categories of Aristotle . • • • .49 2. Ambiguity of the most general names 3. Peelings, or states of consciousness • • 54 4. Feelings must be distinguished from their physical antece dents. Perceptions, what . • • .56 5. Volitions, and Actions, what .... 6. Substance and Attribute . . • « .59 7. Body 61 8. Mind . ... 67 9. Qualities . . • 10. Relations . . .... 72 11. Resemblance ..... 12. Quantity . . .... 78 13. All attributes of bodies are grounded on states of con- 7Q sciousness ....•• 14. So also all attributes of mind . . • .80 15. Recapitulation . . • • • .81 CHAPTER IV. Of Propositions. § 1. Nature and office of the copula 2. Affirmative and Negative propositions . . .87 3. Simple and Complex .... 4. Universal, Particular, and Singular • 93 CHAPTER V. Of the Import of Propositions. § 1. Doctrine that a proposition is the expression of a relation between two ideas . ... 96 2. Doctrine that it is the expression of a relation between the meanings of two names . . • • .99 3. Doctrine that it consists in referring something to, or ex cluding something from, a class . • • 103 4. What it really is . . . • » . 107 5. It asserts (or denies) a sequence, a coexistence, a simple existence, a causation . 6. — or a resemblance . ^" 7. Propositions of which the terms are abstract . • 115 CONTENTS. xiil CHAPTEE VI. Of Propositions merely Verb a I. PAGE § 1. Essential and Accidental propositions . . . 119 2. All essential propositions are identical propositions . 120 3. Individuals have no essences .... 124 4. Seal propositions, how distinguished from verbal . 126 5. Two modes of representing the import of a Heal proposition 127 CHAPTER VII. Of the Nature of Classification, and the Five Predicdbles. § 1. Classification, how connected with Naming . . 129 2. The Predicables, what . . . . .131 3. Genus and Species ...... 131 4. Kinds have a real existence in nature . . . 134 5. Differentia ....... 139 6. Differentiae for general purposes, and differentiae for special or technical purposes ..... 141 7. Proprium . . . . . . 144 8. Accidens ....... 145 CHAPTEB VIII. Of Definition. § 1. A definition, what ...... 148 2. Every name can be defined, whose meaning is susceptible of analysis ...... 150 3. Complete, how distinguished from incomplete definitions . 152 3. — and from descriptions . . . . ' . 154 5. What are called definitions of Things, are definitions of Names with an implied assumption of the existence of Things corresponding to them .... 157 6. — even when such things do not in reality exist . . 165 7. Definitions, though of names only, must be grounded on knowledge of the corresponding Things XIV CONTENTS. BOOK II. OF REASONING. CHAPTEE I. Of Inference, or Seasoning, in general. PAGE § 1. Eetrospect of the preceding book .... 175 2. Inferences improperly so called .... 177 3. Inferences proper, distinguished into inductions and ratio cinations ....... 181 CHAPTER II. Of Ratiocination, or Syllogism. § 1. Analysis of the Syllogism ..... 184 2. The dictum de omni not the foundation of reasoning, but a mere identical proposition .... 191 3. What is the really fundamental axiom of Ratiocination . 196 4. The other form of the axiom .... 199 CHAPTEE III. Of the Functions, and Logical Value, of the Syllogism. ^»» § 1. Is the syllogism a petitio principii ? . . . 202 2. Insufficiency of the common theory . . . 203 3. All inference is from particulars to particulars . . 205 4. General propositions are a record of such inferences, and the rules of the syllogism are rules for the interpretation of the record ...... 214 5. The syllogism not the type of reasoning, but a test of it . 218 6. The true type, what . . . . .222 7. Relation between Induction and Deduction . . 226 8. Objections answered ..... 227 9. Of Formal Logic, and its relation to the Logic of Truth . 231 CHAPTEE IV. Of Trains of Reasoning, and Deductive Sciences, 1. For what purpose trains of reasoning exist . . 234 2. A train of reasoning is a series of inductive inferences . 234 3. — from particulars to particulars through marks of marks 237 4. Why there are deductive sciences .... 240 5. Why other sciences still remain experimental . . 244 6. Experimental sciences may become deductive by the pro gress of experiment ..... 246 7. In what manner this usually takes place . . . 247 CONTENTS. XV CHAPTER V. Of Demonstration, and Necessary Truths. Tftf~*+>** PA&E § 1. The Theorems of geometry are necessary truths only in the sense of necessarily following from hypotheses . 251 2. Those hypotheses are real facts with some of their circum stances exaggerated or omitted .... 255 3. Some of the first principles of geometry are axioms, and these are not hypothetical .... 256 4. — but are experimental truths .... 258 5. An objection answered ..... 261 6. Dr. WhewelTs opinions on axioms examined . . 264 CHAPTER VI. The same Subject continued. § 1. All deductive sciences are inductive . . . 281 2. The propositions of the science of number are not verbal, but generalizations from experience . . . 284 3. In what sense hypothetical ..... 289 4. The characteristic property of demonstrative science is to be hypothetical ...... 290 5. Definition of demonstrative evidence . . . 292 CHAPTER VII. ^Examination of some Opinions opposed to the preceding doctrines. § 1. Doctrine of the Universal Postulate . . . 294 2. The test of inconceivability does not represent the aggre gate of past experience ..... 296 3. — nor is implied in every process of thought . . 299 4. Sir W. Hamilton's opinion on the Principles of Contra diction and Excluded Middle .... 306 \ BOOK III. OF INDUCTION. CHAPTER I. Preliminary Observations on Induction in general. § 1. Importance of an Inductive Logic .... 313 2. The logic of science is also that of business and life . 314 CHAPTER II. Of Inductions improperly so called. § 1. Inductions distinguished from verbal transformations . 319 2. — from inductions, falsely so called, in mathematics . 321 3. — and from descriptions ..... 323 4. Examination of Dr. Whewell's theory of Induction . 326 5. Further illustration of the preceding remarks . . 336 XVI * A* i/ 2 dnj CONTENTS. IHAPTER III. On the Ground of Induction. PAGE 341 §1 3. MM9' Axiom of the uniformity of the course of nature . Not true in every sense. Induction per enumeration*™ .. . 346 stmplicem . • The question of Inductive Logic stated . CHAPTER IV. Of Laws of Nature. The general regularity in nature is a tissue of partial re gularities, called laws . Scientific induction must be grounded on previous spon- . -, ,• o55 taneous inductions . ^ • Are there any inductions fitted to be a test of all others P CHAPTER V. Of the Law of Universal Causation. The universal law of successive phenomena is the Law of Causation . • • • • * . — i. e. the law that every consequent has an invariable antecedent ... The cause of a phenomenon is the assemblage of its con ditions . The distinction of agent and patient illusory The cause is not the invariable antecedent, but the uncon ditional invariable antecedent . Can a cause be simultaneous with its effect P Idea of a Permanent Cause, or original natural agent . Uniformities of coexistence between effects of different permanent causes, are not laws . Doctrine that volition is an efficient cause, examined 360 363 365 373 375 380 383 386 387 CHAPTER VI. Of the Composition of Causes. 8 1. Two modes of the conjunct action of causes, the mechani- -i 4iOo cal and the chemical . 2. The composition of causes the general rule ; the other case exceptional . • 3. Are effects proportional to their causes? . . .. *» CHAPTER VII. Of Observation and Experiment. § 1. The first step of inductive inquiry is a mental analysis of complex phenomena into their elements . . • 414 2. The next is an actual separation of those elements . 416 3. Advantages of experiment over observation . • 417 4. Advantages of observation over experiment . • 420 CONTENTS. CHAPTEE VIII. Of the Four Methods of Experimental Inquiry. PAGE § 1. Method of Agreement ..... 425 2. Method of Difference .... 428 3. Mutual relation of these two methods . . . 429 4. Joint Method of Agreement and Difference . . 433 5. Method of Residues ..... 436 6. Method of Concomitant Variations . . . 437 7. Limitations of this last method .... 443 CHAPTEE IX. Miscellaneous Examples of the Four Methods. § 1. Liebig's theory of metallic poisons . . 449 2. Theory of induced electricity . . . 453 3. Dr. Wells' theory of dew .... 457 4. Dr. Brown-Sequard's theory of cadaveric rigidity . 465 5. Examples of the Method of Residues . . 471 6. Dr. Whewell's objections to the Four Methods . . 475 CHAPTEB X. Of Plurality of Causes ; and of the Intermixture of Effects. § 1. One effect may have several causes . . . 482 2. — which is the source of a characteristic imperfection of the Method of Agreement ... 483 3. Plurality of Causes, how ascertained . . . 487 4. Concurrence of Causes which do not compound their effects 489 5. Difficulties of the investigation, when causes compound their effects ...... 494 6. Three modes of investigating the laws of complex effects 499 7. The method of simple observation inapplicable . . 500 8. The purely experimental method inapplicable . . 501 CHAPTEE XI. Of the Deductive Method. § 1. First stage ; ascertainment of the laws of the separate causes by direct induction . . . 507 2. Second stage ; ratiocination from the simple laws of the complex cases ...... 512 3. Third stage; verification by specific experience . . 514 CONTENTS. CHAPTER XII. Of the Explanation of Laws of Nature. PAGE § 1. Explanation defined • • 518 2. First mode of explanation, by resolving the law of a com plex effect into the laws of the concurrent causes and the fact of their coexistence . . ' . . ' 518 3. Second mode ; by the detection of an intermediate link in the sequence . 4. Laws are always resolved into laws more general than themselves . ... 520 5. Third mode ; the subsumption of less general laws under a more general one . "** 6. What the explanation of a law of nature amounts to . 526 CHAPTER XIII. Miscellaneous Examples of the Explanation of Laws of Nature. § 1. The general theories of the sciences . • .529 2. Examples from chemical speculations 3. Example from Dr. Brown- Sequard's researches on the nervous system . . • • ' 4. Examples of following newly-discovered laws into their complex manifestations . 5. Examples of empirical generalizations, afterwards con firmed and explained deductively 6. Example from mental science . . . 538 7. Tendency of all the sciences to become deductive . 539 INTBODUCTION. § 1. THERE is as great diversity among authors in the modes which they have adopted of defining logic, as in their treatment of the details of it. This is what might naturally be expected on any subject on which writers have availed them selves of the same language as a means of delivering different ideas. Ethics and jurisprudence are liable to the remark in common with logic. Almost every writer having taken a different view of some of the particulars which these branches of knowledge are usually understood to include ; each has so framed his definition as to indicate beforehand his own peculiar tenets, and sometimes to beg the question in their favour. This diversity is not so much an evil to be complained of, as an inevitable and in some degree a proper result of the imperfect state of those sciences. It is not to be expected that there should be agreement about the definition of anything, until there is agreement about the thing itself. To define, is to select from among all the properties of a thing, those which shall be understood to be designated and declared by its name; and the properties must be well known to us before we can be competent to determine which of them are fittest to be chosen for this purpose. Accordingly, in the case of so complex an aggregation of particulars as are compre hended in anything which can be called a science, the defini tion we set out with is seldom that which a more extensive knowledge of the subject shows to be the most appropriate. Until we know the particulars themselves, we cannot fix upon the most correct and compact mode of circumscribing them by a general description. It was not until after an extensive and accurate acquaintance with the details of chemical phenomena, VOL. I. 1 2 INTRODUCTION. that it was found possible to frame a rational definition of chemistry ; and the definition of the science of life and orga nization is still a matter of dispute. So long as the sciences are imperfect, the definitions must partake of their imperfec tion ; and if the former are progressive, the latter ought to he so too. As much, therefore, as is to he expected from a defi nition placed at the commencement of a subject, is that it should define the scope of our inquiries : and the definition which I am about to offer of the science of logic, pretends to nothing more, than to be a statement of the question which I have put to myself, and which this book is an attempt to resolve. The reader is at liberty to object to it as a definition of logic ; but it is at all events a correct definition of the sub ject of these volumes. § 2. Logic has often been called the Art of Seasoning. A writer* who has done more than any other person to restore this study to the rank from which it had fallen in the esti mation of the cultivated class in our own country, has adopted the above definition with an amendment ; he has defined Logic to be the Science, as well as the Art, of reasoning ; meaning by the former term, the analysis of the mental process which takes place whenever we reason, and by the latter, the rules, grounded on that analysis, for conducting the process cor rectly. There can be no doubt as to the propriety of the emendation. A right understanding of the mental process itself, of the conditions it depends on, and the steps of which it consists, is the only basis on which a system of rules, fitted for the direction of the process, can possibly be founded. Art necessarily presupposes knowledge ; art, in any but its infant state, presupposes scientific knowledge : and if every art does not bear the name of a science, it is only because several sciences are often necessary to form the groundwork of a single art. So complicated are the conditions which govern our prac tical agency, that to enable one thing to be done, it is often requisite to know the nature and properties of many things. * Archbishop Whately. DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC. 3 Logic, then, comprises the science of reasoning, as well as an art, founded on that science. But the word Reasoning, again, like most other scientific terms in popular use, abounds in ambiguities. In one of its acceptations, it means syllogizing ; or the mode of inference which may be called (with sufficient accuracy for the present purpose) concluding from generals to particulars. In another of its senses, to reason is simply to infer any assertion, from assertions already admitted : and in this sense induction is as much entitled to be called reasoning as the demonstrations of geometry. Writers on logic have generally preferred the former accep tation of the term : the latter, and more extensive significa tion is that in which I mean to use it. I do this by virtue of the right I claim for every author, to give whatever provi sional definition he pleases of his own subject. But sufficient reasons will, I believe, unfold themselves as we advance, why this should be not only the provisional but the final definition. It involves, at all events, no arbitrary change in the meaning of the word ; for, with the general usage of the English lan guage, the wider signification, I believe, accords better than the more restricted one. § 3. But Reasoning, even in the widest sense of which the word is susceptible, does not seem to comprehend all that is included, either in the best, or even in the most current, conception of the scope and province of our science. The employment of the word Logic to denote the theory of argu mentation, is derived from the Aristotelian, or, as they are commonly termed, the scholastic, logicians. Yet even with them, in their systematic treatises, argumentation was the subject only of the third part: the two former treated of Terms, and of Propositions ; under one or other of which heads were also included Definition and Division. By some, indeed, these previous topics were professedly introduced only on account of their connexion with reasoning, and as a prepara tion for the doctrine and rules of the syllogism. Yet they were treated with greater minuteness, and dwelt on at greater length, than was required for that purpose alone. More recent 1—2 * INTRODUCTION. writers on logic have generally understood the term as it was employed by the able author of the Port Koyal Logic ; viz. as equivalent to the Art of Thinking. Nor is this acceptation confined to books, and scientific inquiries. Even in ordinary conversation, the ideas connected with the word Logic include at least precision of language, and accuracy of classification : and we perhaps oftener hear persons speak of a logical arrange ment, or of expressions logically defined, than of conclusions logically deduced from premises. Again, a man is often called a great logician, or a man of powerful logic, not for the accu racy of his deductions, but for the extent of his command over premises ; because the general propositions required for explaining a difficulty or refuting a sophism, copiously and promptly occur to him : because, in short, his knowledge, besides being ample, is well under his command for argumen tative use. Whether, therefore, we conform to the practice of those who have made the subject their particular study, or to that of popular writers and common discourse, the province of logic will include several operations of the intellect not usually considered to fall within the meaning of the terms Reasoning and Argumentation. These various operations might be brought within the com pass of the science, and the additional advantage be obtained of a very simple definition, if, by an extension of the term, sanctioned by high authorities, we were to define logic as the science which treats of the operations of the human under standing in the pursuit of truth. For to this ultimate end, naming, classification, definition, and all other operations over which logic has ever claimed jurisdiction, are essentially sub sidiary. They may all be regarded as contrivances for enabling a person to know the truths which are needful to him, and to know them at the precise moment at which they are needful. Other purposes, indeed, are also served by these operations ; for instance, that of imparting our knowledge to others. But, viewed with regard to this purpose, they have never been con sidered as within the province of the logician. The sole object of Logic is the guidance of one's own thoughts : the com munication of those thoughts to others falls under the con- DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC. 5 sideration of Khetoric, in the large sense in which that art was conceived hy the ancients ; or of the still more extensive art of Education. Logic takes cognizance of our intellectual operations, only as they conduce to our own knowledge, and to our command over that knowledge for our own uses. If there were hut one rational being in the universe, that being might be a perfect logician; and the science and art of logic would be the same for that one person as for the whole human race. § 4. But, if the definition which we formerly examined included too little, that which is now suggested has the oppo site fault of including too much. Truths are known to us in two ways : some are known directly, and of themselves ; some through the medium of other truths. The former are the subject of Intuition, or Con sciousness ;* the latter, of Inference. The truths known by intuition are the original premises from which all others are inferred. Our assent to the conclusion being grounded on the truth of the premises, we never could arrive at any knowledge by reasoning, unless something could be known antecedently to all reasoning. Examples of truths known to us by immediate conscious ness, are our own bodily sensations and mental feelings. I know directly, and of my own knowledge, that I was vexed yesterday, or that I am hungry to-day. Examples of truths which we know only by way of inference, are occurrences which took place while we were absent, the events recorded in history, or the theorems of mathematics. The two former we infer from the testimony adduced, or from the traces of those past occurrences which still exist ; the latter, from the pre mises laid down in books of geometry, under the title of defi nitions and axioms. Whatever we are capable of knowing * I use these terms indiscriminately, because, for the purpose in view, there is no need for making any distinction between them. But metaphysicians usually restrict the name Intuition to the direct knowledge we are supposed to have of things external to our minds, and Consciousness to our knowledge of our own mental phenomena. 6 INTRODUCTION. must belong to the one class or to the other ; must be in the number of the primitive data, or of the conclusions which can be drawn from these. With the original data, or ultimate premises of our know ledge ; with their number or nature, the mode in which they J are obtained, or the tests by which they may be distinguished ; logic, in a direct way at least, has, in the sense in which I con ceive the science, nothing to do. These questions are partly not a subject of science at all, partly that of a very different science. Whatever is known to us by consciousness, is known be yond possibility of question. What one sees or feels, whether bodily or mentally, one cannot but be sure that one sees or feels. No science is required for the purpose of establishing such truths ; no rules of art can render our knowledge of them more certain than it is in itself. There is no logic for this portion of our knowledge. But we may fancy that we see or feel what we in reality infer. A truth, or supposed truth, which is really the result of a very rapid inference, may seem to be apprehended intui tively. It has long been agreed by thinkers of the most oppo site schools, that this mistake is actually made in so familiar an instance as that of the eyesight. There is nothing of which we appear to ourselves to be more directly conscious, than the distance of an object from us. Yet it has long been ascertained, that what is perceived by the eye, is at most nothing more than a variously coloured surface ; that when we fancy we see distance, all we really see is certain variations of apparent size, and degrees of faintness of colour; that our estimate of the object's distance from us is the result partly of a rapid inference from the muscular sensations accompanying the adjustment of the focal distance of the eye to objects unequally remote from us, and partly of a comparison (made with so much rapidity that we are unconscious of making it) between the size and colour of the object as they appear at the time, and the size and colour of the same or of similar objects as they appeared when close at hand, or when their degree of remoteness was known by other evidence. The perception of distance by the DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC. 7 eye, which seems so like intuition, is thus, in reality, an infe rence grounded on experience; an inference, too, which we learn to make ; and which we make with more and more cor rectness as our experience increases ; though in familiar cases it takes place so rapidly as to appear exactly on a par with those perceptions of sight which are really intuitive, our per ceptions of colour.* Of the science, therefore, which expounds the operations of the human understanding in the pursuit of truth, one essential part is the inquiry : What are the facts which are the objects of intuition or consciousness, and what are those which we merely infer ? But this inquiry has never been considered a portion of logic. Its place is in another and a perfectly distinct department of science, to which the name metaphysics more particularly belongs : that portion of mental philosophy which attempts to determine what part of the furniture of the mind belongs to it originally, and what part is constructed out of materials furnished to it from without. To this science apper tain the great and much debated questions of the existence of matter ; the existence of spirit, and of a distinction between it and matter ; the reality of time and space, as things without the mind, and distinguishable from the objects which are said to exist in them. For in the present state of the discussion on these topics, it is almost universally allowed that the existence of matter or of spirit, of space or of time, is in its nature un susceptible of being proved j and that if anything is known of them, it must be by immediate intuition. To the same science belong the inquiries into the nature of Conception, Perception, Memory, and Belief; all of which are operations of the under standing in the pursuit of truth ; but with which, as phenomena of the mind, or with the possibility which may or may not exist of analysing any of them into simpler phenomena, the * This important theory has of late been called in question by a writer of deserved reputation, Mr. Samuel Bailey ; but I do not conceive that the grounds on which it has been admitted as an established doctrine for a century past, have been at all shaken by that gentleman's objections. I have elsewhere said what appeared to me necessary in reply to his arguments. ( Westminster Review for October 1842 ; reprinted in Dissertations and Discussions, vol. ii.) 8 INTRODUCTION. logician as such has no concern. To this science must also be referred the following, and all analogous questions : To what extent our intellectual faculties and our emotions are innate — to what extent the result of association : Whether God, and duty, are realities, the existence of which is manifest to us ut proof supposes something provable, which must be a Proposition or Assertion ; since nothing but a Proposition can be an object of belief, or therefore of proof. A Proposition is, discourse which affirms or denies something of some other thing. This is one step : there must, it seems, be two things concerned in every act of belief. But what are these Things ? They can be no other than those signified by the two names, which being joined together by a copula constitute the Proposition. If, therefore, we knew what all names signify, we should know everything which in the existing state of human knowledge, is capable either of being made a subject of affirmation or denial, or of being itself affirmed or denied of a subject We have accordingly, in the preceding chapter, reviewed the various kinds of Names, in order to ascertain what is signified by each of them. And we have now carried this survey far enough to be able to take an account of its results, and to exhibit an enumeration of all kinds of Things which are capable of being made predi cates, or of having anything predicated of them : after which to determine the import of Predication, that is, of Proposi tions, can be no arduous task. The necessity of an enumeration of Existences, as the basis of Logic, did not escape the attention of the schoolmen, and of their master Aristotle, the most comprehensive, if not also the most sagacious, of the ancient philosophers. The Cate gories, or Predicaments — the former a Greek word, the latter its literal translation in the Latin language — were intended by him and his followers as an enumeration of all things capable VOL. i. 4 50 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. of being named ; an enumeration by the summa genera, i.e. the most extensive classes into, which things could be distri buted ; which, therefore, were so many highest Predicates, o"ue or other of which was supposed capable of being affirmed with truth of every nameable thing whatsoever. The follow ing are the classes into which, according to this school of philosophy, Things in general might be reduced :— Ovffia, Substantia. Hoabv, Quantitas. Hoiov, Qualitas. ITpoc TI, Relatio. Houtv, Actio. Hd Passio. Ho?-, Ubi. HOTI, Quando. KelaOai, Situs. Habitus. The imperfections of this classification are too obvious to require, and its merits are not sufficient to reward, a minute examination. It is a mere catalogue of the distinctions rudely marked out by the language of familiar life, with little or no attempt to penetrate, by philosophic analysis, to the rationale even of those common distinctions. Such an analysis, how ever superficially conducted, would have shown the enumera tion to be both redundant and defective. Some objects are omitted, and others repeated several times under different heads. It is like a division of animals into men, quadrupeds, horses, asses, and ponies. That, for instance, could not be a very comprehensive view of the nature of Kelation which could exclude action, passivity, and local situation from that cate gory. The same observation applies to the categories Quando (or position in time), and Ubi (or position in space) ; while the distinction between the latter and Situs is merely verbal. The incongruity of erecting into a summum genus the class which forms the tenth category is manifest. On the other hand, the enumeration takes no notice of anything besides substances and attributes. In what category are we to place sensations, or any other feelings and states of mind ; as hope, joy, fear; sound, smell, taste; pain, pleasure; thought, judg- THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 51 ment, conception, and the like? Probably all these would have been placed by the Aristotelian scbool in the categories of actio and pas.sio ; and the relation of such of them as are active, to tbeir objects, and of such of them as are passive, to their causes, would rightly be so placed; but tbe things themselves, the feelings or states of mind, wrongly. Feelings, or states of consciousness, are assuredly to be counted among realities, but they cannot be reckoned either among substances or attributes. § 2. Before recommencing, under better auspices, the attempt made with such imperfect success by the great founder of the science of logic, we must take notice of an unfortunate ambiguity in all the concrete names which correspond to the most general of all abstract terms, the word Existence. When we have occasion for a name which shall be capable of denoting whatever exists, as contradistinguished from non-entity or Nothing, there is hardly a word applicable to the purpose which is not also, and even more familiarly, taken in a sense in which it denotes only substances. But substances are not all that exists ; attributes, if such things are to be spoken of, must be said to exist ; feelings certainly exist Yet when we speak of an object, or of a thing, we are almost always sup posed to mean a substance. There seems a kind of contra diction in using such an expression as that one thing is merely an attribute of another thing. And the announcement of a Classification of Things would, I believe, prepare most readers for an enumeration like those in natural history, beginning with the great divisions of animal, vegetable, and mineral, and subdividing them into classes and orders. If, rejecting the word Thing, we endeavour to find another of a more general import, or at least more exclusively confined to that general import, a word denoting all that exists, and connoting only simple existence ; no word might be presumed fitter for such a purpose than being : originally the present participle of a verb which in one of its meanings is exactly equivalent to the verb exists ; and therefore suitable, even by its grammatical formation, to be the concrete of the abstract existence. But this 4—2 52 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. word, strange as the fact may appear, is still more completely spoiled for the purpose which it seemed expressly made for, than the word Thing. Being is, by custom, exactly synony mous with substance ; except that it is free from a slight taint of a second ambiguity; being applied impartially to matter and to mind, while substance, though originally and in strict ness applicable to both, is apt to suggest in preference the idea of matter Attributes are never called Beings ; nor are feel ings. A Being is that which excites feelings, and which pos sesses attributes. The soul is called a Being; God and angels are called Beings ; but if we were to say, extension, colour, wisdom, virtue, are beings, we should perhaps be suspected of thinking with some of the ancients, that the cardinal virtues are animals; or, at the least, of holding with the Platonic school the doctrine of self-existent Ideas, or with the fol lowers of Epicurus that of Sensible Forms, which detach themselves in every direction from bodies, and by coming in contact with our organs, cause our perceptions. We should be supposed, in short, to believe that Attributes are Substances. In consequence of this perversion of the word Being, phi losophers looking about for something to supply its place, laid their hands upon the word Entity, a piece of barbarous Latin, invented by the schoolmen to be used as an abstract name, in which class its grammatical form would seem to place it ; but being seized by logicians in distress to stop a leak in their terminology, it has ever since been used as a concrete name. The kindred word essence, born at the same time and of the same parents, scarcely underwent a more complete transforma tion when,, from being the abstract of the verb to be, it came to denote something sufficiently concrete to be enclosed in a glass bottle. The word Entity, since it settled down into a concrete name, has retained its universality of signification somewhat less impaired than any of the names before men tioned. Yet the same gradual decay to which, after a certain age, all the language of psychology seems liable, has been at work even here. If you call virtue an entity, you are indeed somewhat less strongly suspected of believing it to be a sub stance than if you called it a being ; but you are by no means THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 53 free from the suspicion. Every word which was originally in tended to connote mere existence, seems, after a long time, to enlarge its connotation to separate existence, or existence freed from the condition of belonging to a substance ; which con dition being precisely what constitutes an attribute, attributes are gradually shut out ; and along with them feelings, which in ninety-nine cases out of a hundred have no other name than that of the attribute which is grounded on them. Strange that when the greatest embarrassment felt by all who have any considerable number of thoughts to express, is to find a sufficient variety of precise words fitted to express them, there should be no practice to which even scientific thinkers are more addicted than that of taking valuable words to express ideas which are sufficiently expressed by other words already appropriated to them. When it is impossible to obtain good tools, the next best thing is to understand thoroughly the defects of those we have. I have therefore warned the reader of the ambiguity of the names which, for want of better, I am necessitated to employ. It must now be the writer's endeavour so to employ them as in no case to leave the meaning doubtful or obscure. No one of the above terms being altogether unambiguous, I shall not confine myself to any one, but shall employ on each occasion the word which seems least likely in the particular case to lead to misunderstanding ; nor do I pretend to use either these or any other words with a rigorous adherence to one single sense. To do so would often leave us without a word to express what is signified by a known word in some one or other of its senses : unless authors had an unlimited licence to coin new words, together with (what it would be more difficult to assume) unlimited power of making readers understand them. Nor would it be wise in a writer, on a subject involving so much of abstraction, to deny himself the advantage derived from even an improper use of a term, when, by means of it, some familiar association is called up which brings the meaning home to the mind, as it were by a flash. The difficulty both to the writer and reader, of the attempt 54 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. which must be made to use vague word's so as to convey a pre- nise meaning, is not wholly a matter of regret. It is not un fitting that logical treatises should afford an example of that, to facilitate which is among the most important uses of logic. Philosophical language will for a long time, and popular lan guage still longer, retain so much of vagueness and ambiguity, that logic would be of little value if it did not, among its other advantages, exercise the understanding in doing its work neatly and correctly with these imperfect tools. After this preamble it is time to proceed to our enumera tion. We shall commence with Feelings, the simplest class of nameable things ; the term Feeling being of course under stood in its most enlarged sense. I. FEELINGS, OR STATES OF CONSCIOUSNESS. § 3. A Feeling and a State of Consciousness are, in the language of philosophy, equivalent expressions : everything is a feeling of which the mind is conscious ; everything which it feels, or, in other words, which forms a part of its own sentient existence. In popular language Feeling is not always synony mous with State of Consciousness ; being often taken more peculiarly for those states which are conceived as belonging to the sensitive, or to the emotional, phasis of our nature, and sometimes, with a still narrower restriction, to the emotional alone, as distinguished from what are conceived as belonging to the percipient or to the intellectual phasis. But this is an admitted departure from correctness of language ; just as, by a popular perversion the exact converse of this, the word Mind is withdrawn from its rightful generality of signification, and restricted to the intellect. The still greater perversion by which Feeling is sometimes confined not only to bodily sensa tions, but to the sensations of a single sense, that of touch, needs not be more particularly adverted to. Feeling, in the proper sense of the term, is a genus, of which Sensation, Emotion, and Thought, are subordinate species. Under the word Thought is here to be included what- THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 55 ever we are internally conscious of when we are said to think ; from the consciousness we have when we think of a red colour without having it before our eyes, to the most recondite thoughts of a philosopher or poet. Be it remembered, how ever, that by a thought is to be understood what passes in the mind itself, and not any object external to the mind, which the person is commonly said to be thinking of. He may be think ing of the sun, or of God, but the sun and God are not thoughts ; his mental image, however, of the sun, and his idea of God, are thoughts ; states of his mind, not of the objects themselves ; and so also is his belief of the existence of the sun, or of God ; or his disbelief, if the case be so. Even imaginary objects (which are said to exist only in our ideas) are to be distinguished from our ideas of them. I may think of a hobgoblin, as I may think of the loaf which was eaten yester day, or of the flower which will bloom to-morrow. But the hobgoblin which never existed is not the same thing with my idea of a hobgoblin, any more than the loaf which once existed is the same thing with my idea of a loaf, or the flower which does not yet exist, but which will exist, is the same with my idea of a flower. They are all, not thoughts, but objects of thought ; though at the present time all the objects are alike non-existent. In like manner, a Sensation is to be carefully distinguished from the object which causes the sensation ; our sensation of white from a white object : nor is it less to be distinguished from the attribute whiteness, which we ascribe to the object in consequence of its exciting the sensation. Unfortunately foi clearness and due discrimination in considering these subjects, our sensations seldom receive separate names. We have a name for the objects which produce in us a certain sensation : the word white. We have a name for the quality in those objects, to which we ascribe the sensation : the name whiteness. But when we speak of the sensation itself (as we have not occasion to do this often except in our scientific speculations), language, which adapts itself for the most part only to the common uses of life, has provided us with no single-worded or immediate designation ; we must employ a circumlocution, and say, The 56 NAMES AND PROPOSITION'S. sensation of white, or The sensation of whiteness ; we must denominate the sensation either from the object, or from the attribute, by which it is excited. Yet the sensation, though it never does, might very well be conceived to exist, without any thing whatever to excite it. We can conceive it as arising spontaneously in the mind. But if it so arose, we should have no name to denote it which would not be a misnomer. In the case of our sensations of hearing we are better provided ; we have the word Sound, and a whole vocabulary of words to denote the various kinds of sounds. For as we are often conscious of these sensations in the absence of any perceptible object, we can more easily conceive having them in the absence of any object whatever. We need only shut our eyes and listen to music, to have a conception of an universe with nothing in it except sounds, and ourselves hearing them : and what is easily con ceived separately, easily obtains a separate name. But in general our names of sensations denote indiscriminately the sensation arid the attribute. Thus, colour stands for the sensations of white, red, &c., but also for the quality in the coloured object. We talk of the colours of things as among their properties. § 4. In the case of sensationsr another distinction has also to be kept in view, which is often confounded, and never with out mischievous consequences. This is, the distinction between the sensation itself, and the state of the bodily organs which precedes the sensation, and which constitutes the physical agency by which it is produced. One of the sources of con fusion on this subject is the division commonly made of feelings into Bodily and Mental. Philosophically speaking, there is no foundation at all for this distinction : even sensations are states of the sentient mind, not states of the body, as distinguished from it. What I am conscious of when I see the colour blue, is a feeling of blue colour, which is one thing ; the picture on my retina, or the phenomenon of hitherto mysterious nature which takes place in my optic nerve or in my brain, is another thing, of which I am not at all conscious, and which scientific investigation alone could have apprised me of. These are states of my body ; but the sensation of blue, which is the con- THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 57 sequence of these states of body, is not a state of body : that which perceives and is conscious is called Mind. When sen sations are called bodily feelings, it is only as being the class of feelings which are immediately occasioned by bodily states ; whereas the other kinds of feelings, thoughts, for instance, or emotions, are immediately excited not by anything acting upon the bodily organs, but by sensations, or by previous thoughts. This, however, is a distinction not in our feelings, but in the agency which produces our feelings: all of them when actually produced are states of mind. Besides the affection of our bodily organs from without, and the sensation thereby produced in our minds, many writers admit a third link in the chain of phenomena, which they call a Perception, and which consists in the recognition of an ex ternal object as the exciting cause of the sensation. This per ception, they say, is an act of the mind, proceeding from its own spontaneous activity ; while in a sensation the mind is passive, being merely acted upon by the outward object. And according to some metaphysicians, it is by an act of the mind, similar to perception, except in not being preceded by any sen sation, that the existence of God, the soul, and other hyper- physical objects is recognised. These acts of what is termed perception, whatever be the conclusion ultimately come to respecting their nature, must, I conceive, take their place among the varieties of feelings or states of mind. In so classing them, I have not the smallest intention of declaring or insinuating any theory as to the law of mind in which these mental processes may be supposed to originate, or the conditions under which they may be legiti mate or the reverse. Far less do I mean (as Dr. Whewell seems to suppose must be meant in an analogous case*) to in dicate that as they are "merely states of mind," it is super fluous to inquire into their distinguishing peculiarities. I abstain from the inquiry as irrelevant to the science of logic. In these so-called perceptions, or direct recognitions by the mind, of objects, whether physical or spiritual, which are ex- * Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, vol. i. p. 40. 58 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. ternal to itself, I can see only cases of belief; but of belief which claims to be intuitive, or independent of external evi dence. When a stone lies before me, I am conscious of certain sensations which I receive from it; but if I say that these sen sations come to me from an external object which I perceive, the meaning of these words is, that receiving the sensations, I intuitively believe that an external cause of those sensations exists. The laws of intuitive belief, and the conditions under which it is legitimate, are a subject which, as we have already so often remarked, belongs not to logic, but to the science of the ultimate laws of the human mind. To the same region of speculation belongs all that can be said respecting the distinction which the German metaphy sicians and their French and English followers so elaborately draw between the acts of the mind and its merely passive states ; between what it receives from, and what it gives to, the crude materials of its experience. I am aware that with reference to the view which those writers take of the primary elements of thought and knowledge, this distinction is funda mental. But for the present purpose, which is to examine, not the original groundwork of our knowledge, but how we come by that portion of it which is not original ; the difference between active and passive states of mind is of secondary im portance. For us, they all are states of mind, they all are feelings ; by which, let it be said once more, I mean to imply nothing of passivity, but simply that they are psychological facts, facts which take place in the mind, and are to be care fully distinguished from the external or physical facts with which they may be connected either as effects or as causes. § 5. Among active states of mind, there is, however, one species which merits particular attention, because it forms a principal part of the connotation of some important classes of names. I mean volitions, or acts of the will. When we speak of sentient beings by relative names, a large portion of the connotation of the name usually consists of the actions of those beings ; actions past, present, and possible or probable future. Take, for instance, the words Sovereign and Subject. What THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 59 meaning do these words convey, but that of innumerable actions, done or to be done by the sovereign and the subjects, to or in regard to one another reciprocally ? So with the words physician and patient, leader and follower, tutor and pupil. In many cases the words also connote actions which would be done under certain contingencies by persons other than those denoted : as the words mortgagor and mortgagee, obligor and obligee, and many other words expressive of legal relation, which connote what a court of justice would do to enforce the legal obligation if not fulfilled. There are also words which connote actions previously done by persons other than those denoted either by the name itself or by its correla tive ; as the word brother. From these instances, it may be seen how large a portion of the connotation of names consists of actions. Now what is an action ? Not one thing, but a series of two things : the state of mind called a volition, fol lowed by an effect. The volition or intention to produce the effect, is one thing ; the effect produced in consequence of the intention, is another thing; the two together constitute the action. I form the purpose of instantly moving my arm ; that is a state of my mind : my arm (not being tied or paralytic) moves in obedience to my purpose ; that is a physical fact, consequent on a state of mind. The intention, followed by the fact, or (if we prefer the expression) the fact when preceded and caused by the intention, is called the action of moving my arm. § 6. Of the first leading division of nameable things, viz. Feelings or States of Consciousness, we began by recognising three sub-divisions ; Sensations, Thoughts, and Emotions. The first two of these we have illustrated at considerable length ; the third, Emotions, not being perplexed by similar ambiguities, does not require similar exemplification. And, finally, we have found it necessary to add to these three a fourth species, commonly known by the name Volitions. Without seeking to prejudge the metaphysical question whether any mental state or phenomenon can be found which is not included in one or other of these four species, it appears 60 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. to me that the amount of illustration bestowed upon these may, so far as we are concerned, suffice for the whole genus. We shall, therefore, proceed to the two remaining classes of name- able things ; all things which are external to the mind being considered as belonging either to the class of Substances or to that of Attributes. II. SUBSTANCES. Logicians have endeavoured to define Substance and Attri bute ; but their definitions are not so much attempts to draw a distinction between the things themselves, as instructions what difference it is customary to make in the grammatical structure of the sentence, according as we are speaking of sub stances or of attributes. Such definitions are rather lessons of English, or of Greek, Latin, or German, than of mental phi losophy. An attribute, say the school logicians, must be the attribute of something; colour, for example, must be the colour of something ; goodness must be the goodness of something : and if this something should cease to exist, or should cease to be connected with the attribute, the existence of the attribute would be at an end. A substance, on the contrary, is self- existent ; in speaking about it, we need not put of after its name. A stone is not the stone of anything; the moon is not the moon of anything, but simply the moon. Unless, indeed, the name which we choose to give to the substance be a re lative name ; if so, it must be followed either by of, or by some other particle, implying, as that preposition does, a reference to something else : but then the other characteristic peculiarity of an attribute would fail ; the something might be destroyed, and the substance might still subsist. Thus, a father must be the father of something, and so far resembles an attribute, in being referred to something besides himself: if there were no child, there would be no father : but this, when we look into the matter, only means that we should not call him father. The man called father might still exist though there were no child, as he existed before there was a child : and there would be no contradiction in supposing him to exist, though the THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 61 whole universe except himself were destroyed. But destroy all white substances, and where would be the attribute white ness ? Whiteness, without any white thing, is a contradiction in terms. This is the nearest approach to a solution of the difficulty, that will be found in the common treatises on logic. It will scarcely be thought to be a satisfactory one. If an attribute is distinguished from a substance by being the attribute of something, it seems highly necessary to understand what is meant by of; a particle which needs explanation too much itself, to be placed in front of the explanation of anything else. And as for the self-existence of substance, it is very true that a substance may be conceived to exist without any other substance, but so also may an attribute without any other attribute : and we can no more imagine a substance without attributes than we can imagine attributes without a substance. Metaphysicians, however, have probed the question deeper, and given an account of Substance considerably more satis factory than this. Substances are usually distinguished as Bodies or Minds. Of each of these, philosophers have at length provided us with a definition which seems unexcep tionable. § 7. A Body, according to the received doctrine of modern metaphysicians, may be defined, the external cause to which we ascribe our sensations. When I see and touch a piece of gold, I am conscious of a sensation of yellow colour, and sensations of hardness and weight ; and by varying the mode of handling, I may add to these sensations many others completely distinct from them. The sensations are 'all of which I am directly conscious ; but I consider them as pro duced by something not only existing independently of my will, but external to my bodily organs and to my mind. This external something I call a body. It may be asked, how come we to ascribe our sensations to any external cause ? And is theiv sufficient ground for so ascribing them ? It is known, that there are metaphysicians 62 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. who have raised a controversy on the point ; maintaining that we are not warranted in referring our sensations to a cause such as we understand by the word Body, or to any external cause whatever. Though we have no concern here with this controversy, nor with the metaphysical niceties on which it turns, one of the best ways of showing what is meant by Sub stance is, to consider what position it is necessary to take up, in order to maintain its existence against opponents. It is certain, then, that a part of our notion of a body consists of the notion of a number of sensations of our own, or of other sentient beings, habitually occurring simultaneously. My conception of the table at which I am writing is com pounded of its visible form and size, which are complex sensa tions of sight ; its tangible form and size, which are complex sensations of our organs of touch and of our muscles ; its weight, which is also a sensation of touch and of the muscles ; its colour, which is a sensation of sight ; its hardness, which is a sensation of the muscles ; its composition, which is another word for all the varieties of sensation which we receive under various circumstances from the wood of which it is made, and so forth. All or most of these various sensations frequently are, and, as we learn by experience, always might be, expe rienced simultaneously, or in many different orders of succes sion, at our own choice : and hence the thought of any one of them makes us think of the others, and the whole becomes mentally amalgamated into one mixed state of consciousness, which, in the language of the school of Locke and Hartley, is termed a Complex Idea. Now, there are philosophers who have argued as follows. If we conceive an orange to be divested of its natural colour without acquiring any new one ; to lose its softness without becoming hard, its roundness without becoming square or pentagonal, or of any other regular or irregular figure what ever ; to be deprived of size, of weight, of taste, of smell ; to lose all its mechanical and all its chemical properties, and acquire no new ones ; to become, in short, invisible, intangible, imperceptible not only by all our senses, but by the senses of all other sentient beings, real or possible ; nothing, say these THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 63 thinkers, would remain. For of what nature, they ask, could be the residuum ? and by what token could it manifest its pre sence ? To the unreflecting its existence seems to rest on the evidence of the senses. But to the senses nothing is apparent except the sensations. We know, indeed, that these sensations are bound together by some law ; they do not come together at random, but according to a systematic order, which is part of the order established in the universe. When we experience one of these sensations, we usually experience the others also, or know that we have it in our power to experience them. But a fixed law of connexion, making the sensations occur together, does not, say these philosophers, necessarily require what is called a substratum to support them. The conception of a substratum is but one of many possible forms in which that connexion presents itself to our imagination ; a mode of, as it were, realizing the idea. If there be such a substratum, suppose it this instant miraculously annihilated, and let the sensations continue to occur in the same order, and how would the substratum be missed ? By what signs should we be able to discover that its existence had terminated ? Should we not have as much reason to believe that it still existed as we now have ? And if we should not then be warranted in believing it, how can we be so now ? A body, therefore, according to these metaphysicians, is not anything intrinsically different from the sensations which the body is said to produce in us ; it is, in short, a set of sensations, or rather, of possibilities of sen sation, joined together according to a fixed law. The controversies to which these speculations have given rise, and the doctrines which have been developed in the attempt to find a conclusive answer to them, have been fruitful of important consequences to the Science of Mind. The sensa tions (it was answered) which we are conscious of, and which we receive, not at random, but joined together in a certain uniform manner, imply not only a law or laws of connexion, but a cause external to our mind, which cause, by its own laws, determines the laws according to which the sensations are connected and experienced. The schoolmen used to call this external cause by the name we have already employed, a 64 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. substratum ; and its attributes (as they expressed themselves) inhered, literally stuck, in it. To this substratum the name Matter is usually given in philosophical discussions. It was soon, however, acknowledged by all who reflected on the sub ject, that the existence of matter cannot be proved by extrinsic evidence. The answer, therefore, now usually made to Berkeley and his followers, is, that the belief is intuitive ; that mankind, in all ages, have felt themselves compelled, by a necessity of their nature, to refer their sensations to an external cause : that even those who deny it in theory, yield to the necessity in practice, and both in speech, thought, and feeling, do, equally with the vulgar, acknowledge their sensations to be the effects of something external to them : this knowledge, therefore, it is affirmed, is as evidently intuitive as our knowledge of our sensations themselves is intuitive. And here the question merges in the fundamental problem of metaphysics properly so called ; to which science we leave it. But although the extreme doctrine of the Idealist meta physicians, that objects are nothing but our sensations and the laws which connect them, has not been generally adopted by subsequent thinkers ; the point of most real importance is one on which those metaphysicians are now very generally considered to have made out their case : viz., that all we know of objects is the sensations which they give us, and the order of the occurrence of those sensations. Kant himself, on this point, is as explicit as Berkeley or Locke. However firmly convinced that there exists an universe of " Things in them selves," totally distinct from the universe of phenomena, or of things as they appear to our senses; and even when bringing into use a technical expression (Noumenori) to denote what the thing is in itself, as contrasted with the representation of it in our minds ; he allows that this representation (the matter of which, he says, consists of our sensations, though the form is given by the laws of the mind itself) is all we know of the object: and that the real nature of the Thing is, and by the constitution of our faculties ever must remain, at least in the present state of existence, an impenetrable mystery to us. " Of things absolutely or in themselves/' says Sir William THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 65 Hamilton,* "be they external, be they internal, we know nothing, or know them only as incognisable ; and become aware of their incomprehensible existence, only as this is in directly and accidentally revealed to us, through certain quali ties related to our faculties of knowledge, and which qualities, again, we cannot think as unconditioned, irrelative, existent in and of themselves. All that we know is therefore pheno menal, — phenomenal of the unknown."f The same doctrine is laid down in the clearest and strongest terms by M. Cousin, whose observations on the subject are the more worthy of attention, as, in consequence of the ultra-German and ontolo- gical character of his philosophy in other respects, they may be regarded as the admissions of an opponent.! There is not the slightest reason for believing that what we call the sensible qualities of the object are a type of any- * Discussions on Philosophy, &c. Appendix I. pp. 643-4. t It is to be regretted that Sir William Hamilton, though he often strenu ously insists on this doctrine, and though, in the passage quoted, he states it with a comprehensiveness and force which leave nothing to be desired, did not consistently adhere to his own doctrine, but maintained along with it 'opinions with which it is utterly irreconcilable. See the third and other chapters of An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy. J " Nous savons qu'il existe quelque chose hors de nous, parceque nous ne pouvons expliquer nos perceptions sans les rattacher a des causes distinctes de nous-memes ; nous savons de plus que ces causes, dont nous ne connaissons pas d'ailleurs 1'essence, produisent les effets les plus variables, les plus divers, et ineme les plus contraires, selon qu'elles rencontrent telle nature ou telle dis position du sujet. Mais savons-nous quelque chose de plus? et m§me, vu le caractere inde'termine' des causes que nous concevons dans les corps, y a-t-il quelque chose de plus a savoir ? Y a-t-il lieu de nous enqueYir si nous per- cevons les choses telles qu'elles sont ? Non eVidemmerit Je ne dis pas que le piobleme est insoluble, je dis qu'il est absurde et enferme une contra diction. Nous ne savons pas ce que ces causes sonl en elles-mtmes, et la raison nous defend de chercher k le connaitre : mais il est bien evident apriori, Belles ne sont pas en elles-mSmes ce qu'elles sont par rapport a nous, puisque la presence du sujet modifie ne"cessairement leur action. Supprimez tout sujet sen tan t, il est certain que ces causes agiraieut encore puisqu'elles continueraient d'exister • raais elles af iraient autrement ; elles seraient encore des qualites et des pro-' price's, mais qui ne ressembleraient a rien de ce que nous connaissons. Le feu ne manifesterait plus aucune des proprietes qutf-nous lui connaissons : que serait-il ? (Test ce que nous ne saurons jamais. Vest d'ailleurs peut-etre un proUeme qui ne repuyne pas seulement a la nature de notre esprit, mais a I' essence meme des choses. Quand meme en effet on supprimerait par la pense'e tous les VOL. I. 5 66 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. thing inherent in itself, or bear any affinity to its own nature. A cause does not, as such, resemble its effects; an east wind is not like the feeling of cold, nor heat like the steam of boil ing water. Why then should matter resemble our sensations ? Why should the inmost nature of fire or water resemble the impressions made by those objects upon our senses ?* Or on what principle are we authorized to deduce from the effects, anything concerning the cause, except that it is a cause ade quate to produce those effects ? It may, therefore, safely be laid down as a truth both obvious in itself, and admitted by all whom it is at present necessary to take into consideration, that, of the outward world, we know and can know absolutely nothing, except the sensations which we experience from it.f sujets sentants, il faudrait encore admettre que nul corps ne manifesterait ses proprie'tes autrement qu'en relation avec un sujet quelconque, et dans ce cas ses proprietes ne seraient encore que relatives: en sorte qu'il me parait fort raisonuable d' admettre que les proprie'te's de'termine'es des corps n'existent pas independamment d'un sujet quelconque, et que quand on demande si les pro prie'te's de la matiere sont telles que nous les percevons, il faudrait voir aupara- vant si elles sont en tant que de"termin