UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY LIBRARY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA. BIOLOGY Class G FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD THE APPEAL TO BIOLOGY OR EVOLUTION FOR HUMAN GUIDANCE BY ROBERT MACKINTOSH M B.D. (EDIN.), M.A., D.D. (GLASG.) PROFESSOR AT LANCASHIRE INDEPENDENT COLLEGE AUTHOR OF " CHRIST AND THE JEWISH LAW " THE MACMILLAN COMPANY LONDON : MACMILLAN & CO., LTD. 1899 dll rights reserved a . H COPYRIGHT, 1899, BY THE MACMILLAN COMPANY. J. S. Cushing & Co. - Berwick & Smith Norwood Mass. U.S.A. DEDICATED WITH WARM REGARD TO rtttenfc principal £>cott B.A., D.D., LL.B. AND TO RECENT AND PRESENT STUDENTS OF LANCASHIRE INDEPENDENT COLLEGE 212343 ItOOM PREFACE THE historical sketch and criticism here attempted had its proximate origin in two consecutive years' work with a senior class of sociology at Lancashire College. In 1896-97 essays were prescribed on topics suggested by Mr. Benjamin Kidd's Social Evolution; while the seniors of 1897-98 attended lectures covering rather more ground. The mate- rial thus collected has been again revised and again considerably added to. The literature of the sub- ject is always growing. Some books of consequence, old or new, must have been overlooked. Still, it is hoped that the subject itself has well-defined limits. The appeal to biology, outlined by Comte, newly defined and emphasised by Darwinism, has now been stated in the most extreme form logically possible. Mr. Kidd's book holds that significant position. In studying the questions raised, the author has found himself, though with certain grave reserves, more and more thrown back upon philosophical principles learned at Glasgow, above twenty years ago, from the present Master of Balliol College. Vlll PREFACE I wish to express thanks for kind help on different points : to Professor Henry Jones of Glasgow Uni- versity; to the Rev. A. Halliday Douglas, Cam- bridge ; and, among others, very special thanks to Professor J. Arthur Thomson and Mr. Norman Wyld. Both Mr. Thomson and Mr. Wyld, while busy with important work on the theory of natural selection, found time to give an amateur valuable information bearing on the meaning and merits of Weismann's doctrine of Panmixia. R. M. CONTENTS CHAPTER I PAGE INTRODUCTORY i PART I COMTISM, WITH SOME SCATTERED PARALLELS CHAPTER II COMTE'S LIFE AND THE PRINCIPLES OF HIS TEACHING . . 10 CHAPTER III THE APPEAL TO BIOLOGY ........ 28 Note A: On " Natural Law in the Spiritual World" . . 35 CHAPTER IV THE APPEAL TO HISTORY 38 CHAPTER V THE DOCTRINE OF ALTRUISM 49 CHAPTER VI COMTE'S LAWGIVING . ... 60 X CONTENTS PART II SIMPLE EVOLUTIONISM — SPENCER, STEPHEN CHAPTER VII PAGE DARWINIAN AND SPENCERIAN CONCEPTIONS OF EVOLUTION — DARWIN ...... ... 65 CHAPTER VIII DARWINIAN AND SPENCERIAN CONCEPTIONS OF EVOLUTION — SPENCER . . .«,..-, . . . . . 76 CHAPTER IX MR. SPENCER'S THREE DOCTRINES OF HUMAN WELFARE . 93 CHAPTER X MR. LESLIE STEPHEN'S "SCIENCE OF ETHICS" . . . 103 PART III DARWINISM, OR STRUGGLE FOR EXISTENCE CHAPTER XI "DARWINISM IN MORALS" — Miss COBBE'S PROTEST . .119 CHAPTER XII DARWINISM IN POLITICS: BAGEHOT . . . . "... .. .124 NoteB: On Professor Ritchie's "Darwinism and Politics" . 132 CONTENTS xi CHAPTER XIII PAGE DARWINISM IN ETHICS: PROFESSOR ALEXANDER . . .134 CHAPTER XIV REACTION FROM DARWINISM: HUXLEY 148 CHAPTER XV REACTION FROM DARWINISM: DRUMMOND'S "ASCENT OF MAN" 154 CHAPTER XVI REITERATION OF DARWINISM: ELIMINATION MADE ABSOLUTE — MR. A. SUTHERLAND 169 CHAPTER XVII THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION . . . .185 PART IV HYPER-DARWINISM — WEISMANN, KIDD CHAPTER XVIII A " FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE " ? . . . . . . 233 CHAPTER XIX HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY: STRUGGLE MADE ABSOLUTE — MR. KIDD 258 CHAPTER XX SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS . „ , „ . .278 ANALYTICAL CONTENTS CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY Science offers to supersede religion as guide to conduct — In form of theoretical sociology — Appealing to biology and evolution — Sociology distinguished from politics — From economics — From social philosophy — Akin to evolutionary ethics — Our point of view; morality taken for granted PART I COMTISM, WITH SOME SCATTERED PARALLELS CHAPTER II COMTE'S LIFE AND THE PRINCIPLES OF HIS TEACHING Comte as founder — His life — His books — The term "Sociology" — " Statics " (cf. Spencer) — " Dynamics " — Divisions of the Polity — Comte's religion — The term "Positive" — Four authorities superseded — Comte on psychology — And on ethics — Law of the three stages — Criticism — Transition to the study of Comte's relation to science — He repudiates dogmatic atheism and mate- rialism— His scale of values in the hierarchy of the sciences — Spencer's criticism CHAPTER III THE APPEAL TO BIOLOGY The "social organism" in other writers — In Comte — Idealist supple- ment to the biological appeal — Professor Mackenzie's statement XIV ANALYTICAL CONTENTS of the idealist view — Intuitionalist criticism of the appeal — Comte uses a biological parable — Consistent phenomenalism means (if not evolutionism) hedonism — Comtism and hedonism two half-truths [Note A. On Drummond's Natural Law in the Spiritual World — " Biological religion," according to Finlayson — Drum- mond appeals to biogenesis — His religion is Calvinistic, rather, or Gnostic — His noble zeal for continuity in knowledge] CHAPTER IV THE APPEAL TO HISTORY In Dr. Hatch — Criticism — In Ritschl, how far Comtist — Other appeals; to historic parallels — Example from Comte — To the -whole tendency of history — More usual in Comte ; examples — Criticism — Mr. Mackenzie's criticism — Guidance to be gained from history is limited — Comte's varied and capricious appeals to it CHAPTER V THE DOCTRINE OF ALTRUISM A fragment of ethics — On a psychological basis — Opposes psycho- logical hedonism — Healthily, but incompetently — Fitzjames Stephen's objection to it; we cannot alter nature's forces! — That is good determinism, but bad morals — Ethically, is a new con- ception of virtue — Scientifically worthless [Mr. Baldwin] — " Bal- ance" is preferred to altruism by Butler at times — By Spencer — Criticism CHAPTER VI COMTE'S LAWGIVING Its principles — The separation of the temporal and spiritual powers — Political character of Comte's sociology — Details — Summary ANALYTICAL CONTENTS XV PART II SIMPLE EVOLUTIONISM — SPENCER, STEPHEN CHAPTER VII DARWINIAN AND SPENCERIAN CONCEPTIONS OF EVOLUTION — DARWIN Evolution came as a surprise — Darwin deals with biology — With species only — Taking "Struggle" from Malthus, he perceives in it (natural) "Selection" — A true cause, but minute; an im- mensely slow process — Compare the replies to Malthus — Sexual Selection accelerating — Or Use-Inheritance — But too much La- marck, making variation not "casual," but purposeful, would render unnecessary the " selective " action of " nature " — Recent doubts as to use-inheritance CHAPTER VIII DARWINIAN AND SPENCERIAN CONCEPTIONS OF EVOLUTION — SPENCER A cosmic philosophy — Resting on correlation of forces — And on hypothesis of organic evolution — Emphasising natural (physical, material) law — Darwinism as a cosmic philosophy? Alexander — Cf. Lotze — Cf. Fiske — Spencer values true use-inheritance as accounting for a priori knowledge — But natural selection is not the source of his laissez faire doctrine; he looks forward to a future " balance " — His relation to embryology — Evolution means growing complexity — In terms of matter — Two other phases — Dissolution as death — As catastrophe — Equilibrium is theoreti- cal and prophetic — Spencer's sequence of the three phases — Criticisms: on the assumed beginning of the process — On its isolation — On equilibrium, as involving a different point of view — Reason is more than a new phase of complexity — The whole process breaks up into a series of separate evolutions in complexity CHAPTER IX MR. SPENCER'S THREE DOCTRINES OF HUMAN WELFARE Goodness is more evolved conduct, i.e. is " wisdom " — An appeal to (cosmic) history ! — It is balance, of egoism and altruism — An XVI ANALYTICAL CONTENTS appeal to economics and to (hedonistic) psychology — It is indi- vidual freedom — An appeal to rights, and to (human) history, emerging from militarism — For which Spencer feels an exag- gerated dread — Spencer masses facts rather than unifies know- ledge— The "social organism" is only a phrase with him CHAPTER X MR. LESLIE STEPHEN'S SCIENCE OF ETHICS Stephen a utilitarian — Who came to believe in evolution as a scien- tific fact — Begins here with facts; ethical judgments exist — Organisms seek maximum efficiency — If social " tissue " is " or- ganic " — Then ethical laws may be the conditions of maximum social efficiency — (Nature cares for individuals) — Nature says, "Be strong! " — Ethics says, "Society, be strong! " — The ethical is the typical society, and therefore ethical judgments are binding — But the type is actual, not ideal ! — Society is a complex whole, changing while its parts are unchanged — Criticism — Sanction for individual goodness lies in sympathy merely — Sometimes we are too good for our own interests ! — Compared with Comte, lacks authority — With Spencer; calls "health " the ideal, and ridicules "balance" — With Darwin; not struggle of individual with indi- vidual, but of individual with society — With Utilitarianism; dis- courages the calculation of consequences — Most of his positions may be accepted in a deeper sense PART III DARWINISM, OR STRUGGLE FOR EXISTENCE CHAPTER XI "DARWINISM IN MORALS" — MISS COBBE'S PROTEST Darwinism may be applied to morals by analogy — Or, as here, by explaining man's evolutionary origin — Miss Cobbe attacks Dar- win's explanation of the rise of morals out of intelligence plus sympathy — And the hypothetical palliation of murder — Little trace of natural selection in Darwin's ethical statement — Darwin's analysis may be accepted, not his view of reason A CONTENTS xvii CHAPTER XII DARWINISM IN POLITICS — BAGEHOT Applies Darwinism by analogy — Evolution transforms imperceptibly — By nerve tissue in our case; but nothing depends on this asser- tion of use-inheritance by Bagehot; it is a mere illustration — Not ethnological, but political questions — Problems both of prog- ress and of differentiation — 1st, Custom as the remedy for primi- tive wildness in the " fit " — Criticism — 2nd, Customs winnowed by the test of war — 3rd, Free discussion — Race blending, etc., as minor factors — Three limitations on the Darwinian principle in Bagehot's application of it [Note B. On Professor Ritchie's Darwinism and Politics — Inconsistency between the different essays — One interesting hint] CHAPTER XIII DARWINISM IN ETHICS — PROFESSOR ALEXANDER Fusion of idealism and naturalism — Moral judgments are facts, but the assertion of free will is absurd — Criticism ; capricious ; ignores the content of moral judgments and the germ of a system in them — Punishment grouped with dynamics? — Statics are truly, though imperfectly, moral — Goodness is a twofold " equilibrium " — This doctrine is enforced against other definitions — In the Dynamics equilibrium is revealed as endlessly changing, and is called " com- promise"— Ideals compete like organisms for survival — Criticism; not (a) true Darwinian struggle, nor (£) true extinction — The new ideals are not wholly new — Ideals are complementary — So far as he Darwinises he is false to morality CHAPTER XIV REACTION FROM DARWINISM — HUXLEY Reaction as to ethics — Due to the vision of struggle and pain — Not sympathy but justice is essential — It must suspend outright the cosmic process — Older evolutionism (Greece, India) gave no guidance — Criticism; nature and spirit are opposed — Yet con- nected, and reason fulfils the cosmic process by transforming it xviii ANALYTICAL CONTENTS CHAPTER XV REACTION FROM DARWINISM — DRUMMOND'S ASCENT OF MAN His precursors — His sympathy for Spencer — His Comtist terminology — Seeks a biological basis for altruism — Corrects Darwin — Not like Miss Cobbe — Largely like Huxley — But seeks a fairer state- ment of the facts — Brings in a second biological function (out of three !), viz. reproduction — Wallace, on the selection of reason — Leads up to doctrine of "Arrest of the Body " — Cf. Cleland on the human skull — Emphasis on maternity and weakness of human infant — Criticism; "egoism" and its struggle purely evil? — Or male sex with its justice ? — Is domesticity = sociality? — Has Drummond shown a factor in progress? — A better philosophy claims all nature for God CHAPTER XVI REITERATION OF DARWINISM: ELIMINATION MADE ABSOLUTE — MR. A. SUTHERLAND A strong book with some weaknesses — Works out the origin of moral feeling by natural selection — Restates Drummond-like position as Darwinian (?) — And exemplifies " arrival " of forms — Biology ; fitness to survive — And to breed, and rear — Quantity first relied on — Then quality — This develops sympathy — Which becomes serviceable — Anthropology ; everything depends on the ap- proaches to monogamy — Sociology ; progress is by elimination of the inferior — Even when it seems to find more rapid means — (Yet he allows some progress by imitation!) — History ; retro- gression is possible ! — For he hates all militarism — On the whole he does not believe in history — Or in reason — Ethics; Has dealt only with one half of goodness ! — Egoism must balance sym- pathy! — Balance will grow automatic! — Criticism; no right to call sympathy moral, if only half of morality — Nature does not select one quality at a time ! — Selection said to have worked — Not true natural selection, though — WThy is goodness not auto- matic already? — Do beauty and goodness exist, or do they not? — "Yes and no ! " ANALYTICAL CONTENTS xix CHAPTER XVII THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION I. Chance in relation to purpose, as accident — As absence of design — In relation to law; as blind law — As blind combination of laws — Compare with the last the scientific or mechanical view of the world; a number of separate substances ruled by a number of independent laws — Good enough for science, not for philosophy — Darwin ought not to assume things as really disconnected, merely because he has not needed to investigate their connection — As if organism and environment were accidentally brought together — Or as if organism and organism were mere rivals — (They are rivals !) — Or as if force and force were disconnected? II. Darwin treats variation as casual, i.e. as a thing with no bearing in itself on the purpose of the species — His theory allows this assumption — But does not prove it — We all habitually under- stand the theory in that sense, e.g. in contrasting natural selection with use-inheritance — On the fact, evidence is wanted — Con- ceivably variation may choose very irregularly between many fixed possibilities — This seems to point back to disconnected laws, as in last section III. Even on Darwin's own view he is hardly entitled to call the process of evolution natural selection — Aggregate range of possi- ble variation is fixed by the nature of the material — Two agencies must be taken together — Of the two the varying organism, not the blindly selecting environment, seems the better to account for rise of new qualities — Summary of I., II., III. IV. Kinds of natural selection, A, B, and C — B exists! — If organic evolution is a fact, C exists ! — Accelerating any other evolutionary force that may exist, and of course involving B — If A is found alongside of C, A must have a separate field where C cannot enter, else inconsiderable — Natural selection (C) lasts as long as nature is nature — Even along with (the more rapid force of) animal intelligence — True reason checks it — Does natural selection ever work by itself (A) ? — Higher animals with fewer births evolve as quickly as lower; has a new force arisen? or was natural selec- tion never the leading force ? — [Can we regard intelligence as the new evolving force? Dr. Mellone assumes its operation every- where !] XX ANALYTICAL CONTENTS V. Can natural selection apply to men? — Biologically — Struggle with beasts is over — Famine (A) is rare, and of doubtful tendency — Pestilence (C) does harm— Vice (B)— Crime (B) — War (selects the wrong way) — Religious celibacy (z^.) — Summary — Socio- logically— Mr. Kidd's insistence on struggle is really biological; is unproved; is not an insistence on natural selection — Ethically — Mr. Alexander's competition of "Ideals" is exaggerated — And itself implies reason and sympathy — Mr. Sutherland's elimination of evil doers ignores positive causes of moral progress — Exempli- fied typically in Jesus Christ VI. If natural selection does not operate where reason and conscience exist, it yet may originate them in the loose and incorrect sense in which natural selection is said to originate things ! — If reason, etc., were, as most suppose, evolved and selected — How selected? — Have adjacent races died out ? VII. Other idealist views — Professor Ritchie praises natural selection more fully, in vague terms and in some passages — Mr. Sandeman rejects it, because he believes in the teleological perfection of every organism — But is it possible to get over the impression produced by rudimentary organs? — It is enough if the whole of nature is good, and its parts relatively Jit — Dr. Stirling believes the casual variation which makes an individual can never make a type — Is it certain that every individual is born differentiated? — Or that any differences are incapable of growing by cumulation into a type ? — Possible value of the hypothesis of natural selec- tion, even if a fiction ANALYTICAL CONTENTS xxi PART IV HYPER-DARWINISM — WEISMANN, KIDD / CHAPTER XVIII A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? An intenser assertion of struggle — Not on ground of experiment; evidence is ambiguous — On ground of a theory of heredity — Darwin's theory (Pangenesis) assumed derivation of embryonic qualities from qualities and tissues of parental organism — Use- inheritance possible or probable on this view — But " Atavism " forced the concession, some " gemmules " had passed on undevel- oped from earlier generations till they found their chance — Galton's figures for resemblance to ancestors — Hence theories asserting " continuity of the germ plasm " — Parable of the hie- rarchy — Galton (" Stirp ") does not absolutely deny the possibility of use-inheritance — But in Weismann's earlier and more consis- tent views, founded on by Mr. Kidd, amphimixis is the only cause of variation — Extrusion of one of the " polar bodies " securing ( ?) non-identity of all offspring of same pair — Permutations and com- binations of qualities of unicellular organisms — Nature selecting fittest adults, and in them best germ plasm — Parable of the suckers — Of the Nile — No new quality arises, but amount of each telling quality increases — Qualities arose originally, Lamarck fashion, from environment, when unicellular life lay open to its pressure — Unicellular organisms (propagating by fission) and germ plasm are potentially immortal — Correlation alleged between sex and (natural) death; now sex is absent from the unicellular world — Natural selection might account for the predominance (if not origin) of sex if Weismann would assume the necessary competition — Romanes alleges that natural selection might ac- count for predominance of habit of dying natural death; but would not death by violence sufficiently prevent any race (immersed in the struggle) from falling into wholesale decrepitude ? — Origin of sex and death a mystery; or " chance " variation ! or effect of molecular constitution of germ plasm ! — Weismann's appeal to " natural selection," while he denies " struggle," is metaphysical in the worst sense — Recapitulation, and note of some of Weis- xxii ANALYTICAL CONTENTS mann's changes of opinion before 1893 — Especially this change: ENVIRONMENT MAY DO SOMETHING TO MODIFY GERM PLASM ! — Making true use-inheritance conceivable, though not inevitable — Mr. Kidd is anachronous — Panmixia, the absence of natural selection, is held to involve indefinite retrogression; important; questionable CHAPTER XIX HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY: STRUGGLE MADE ABSOLUTE — MR. KIDD Resemblance to Comte — Intenser emphasis on biology [cf. Mr. Platt- Ball] — (i) Panmixia = degeneration is inconsistent with dreams of socialism or of final balance — Selfishness, however, may not care for remote consequences — [Ought Panmixia further to imply extinction?] Also, social "statics" are blotted out — And evolu- tion becomes almost identical with progress — Could not Mr. Kidd save many essential positions without this assumption? — (2) Next, if progress implies struggle — And selfish reason makes unwilling to struggle for good of the race, supernatural counterpoise of religion must help, as hitherto — Now, Weismann had riddled his own position with qualifications — Kidd also appeals to biology by a doctrine of the social organism; but everything here depends on philosophy, not biology — (3) First, the doctrine of reason; reason is formal, as with A. J. Balfour, Darwin, Drummond — For Mr. Kidd also holds that biological law applies without a break to rational man — Yet reason disturbs process of evolution — And Bagehot, Stephen, Drummond have noted other changes due to it — Can it be wholly evil? — Balfour and Kidd repudiate Kant or Coleridge's deeper sense of " reason " — But they cannot avoid such sense if it lies in the word and in the fact — (4) Secondly, doctrine of religion as anti-rational — Not = "future judgment"; that is rational ! — Can we believe the irrational ? — Does not Kidd tamper with Christian equalitarianism? — Biologically; variation may be purposeful and professive — Historically; reason is pro- gressive; by rational methods — Religion its fulfilment — It needs a force to give it motive and constancy ANALYTICAL CONTENTS xxiii CHAPTER XX SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS Self-contradictions — Comte is arbitrary — Biology has been reinforced by evolutionary theories, yielding different forms of sociological doctrine — I . Analogy, without struggle, Stephen — 2. Continuity, without struggle, Spencer, Alexander (partly) — 3. Analogy of Darwinism, Bagehot, Alexander, Ritchie (?) — 4. Continuity of natural selection, Sutherland, Drummond(?), Kidd — None of these wholly succeed; Old authorities will return ! — Or idealism, which is compatible with the old authorities, may give us a more satisfy- ing doctrine of evolution — What have we been taught? — (i) A social organism exists — Idealism reinforces this lesson — (2) Strug- gle has been useful; will it not be? as discussion? as competition? • — In light of idealism this seems possible — Of fact, probable — Must not exaggerate its place; it is subordinate in life of reason — [Mallock] — Finally, does progressiveness of evolution make it a guide to conduct? — Difficulties in biology ; environment constant? — Some forms have stopped ! — Some never started ! — Differentia- tion plainer here than progress — Reason makes for progress in his- tory— Is it all-sufficient? (Mill, Buckle) — Ancient civilisation failed — Morality and Christianity must safeguard modern civilisation FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY Science offers to supersede religion as guide to conduct — In form of theoretical sociology — Appealing to biology and evolution — Soci- ology distinguished from politics — From economics — From social philosophy — Akin to evolutionary ethics — Our point of view; morality taken for granted WHEN the French garrison left Rome in 1870, fears were openly expressed that anarchy would break out, but the Italian troops were promptly marched in, and all went quietly. Religion is supposed to be a retreating force in modern life, and many, even of those who are no friends to religion, suffer grave apprehensions as they look forward to a state of society emancipated from all religious restraint; but others tell us that science will find a remedy. Religion may go off duty, but science will take its place. Never was this concep- tion more confidently advanced, or with more elabo- ration, than in the first founding of sociology under its present name. We must clear the ground, however, by a distinc- tion. It is theoretical sociology that we have in 2 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD CHAP. view, — a coherent, deliberate body of doctrines, making, among other claims, the startling claim which we have noted above. Much that goes under the name of sociology is matter of quite a different kind. We may call it practical sociology, and we may describe it as a somewhat formless mass of good intentions. In detail it offers many valuable suggestions ; scientifically it is a thing of naught. If we were foolish enough to busy ourselves with it in this discussion we should be embarking on unknown waters, possibly upon a shoreless sea. We shall therefore take nothing to do with practical sociology. It is the science or alleged science of sociology that claims our attention! One outstanding feature of this science is its con- nection with biology. In the early days of modern history, mathematics stood out in sharp and isolated relief as a well-finished and well-formulated science. Hence an impression got abroad that other sciences were to be perfected by treatment on mathematical lines. Spinoza's Ethics, with its array of definitions, postulates, and axioms, and with its pedantic series of syllogisms, is only the most celebrated and most notable among many similar attempts. In our time, biology seems to have cast a like spell upon the minds of not a few. It is biology nowadays which threatens to invade and annex every province of thought. Already in Auguste Comte, the founder or the godfather of sociology, biology counts for a great deal, and subsequent evolutionary speculation has enlarged its claims to infinity. If we achieve anything in this essay, it will probably be in the way of .finding a definition (or a cluster of definitions) for I INTRODUCTORY 3 the fascinating term " evolution," and in forming an estimate of the value which it, or which they, may possess as affording guidance to human conduct. Let us further clear our thoughts before beginning our investigation by endeavouring to "place" soci- ology, provisionally, in relation to other kindred sciences. In contrast with Politics, sociology deals with the informal or unintended * results of human associ- ation. In ancient days the line of division scarcely existed. The conception of a natural growth had never been applied to society. Speculation in early times was exceedingly sanguine, and counted upon refashioning society at its pleasure. We have learned from age-long experience that human nature is not so easily tamed or managed, even by those who try to manage it for its own good. We turn away incredulously from stories of a lawgiver who stamped his own personality and ideas upon many generations. Perhaps we go too far in our recoil from the ancient belief in the powers of the wise man. He may not always have been a myth ; his results might even be repeated. And yet, essen- tially, we are in the right. " All the world," as we say, is wiser than anybody in the world. To take a more definite example, the House of Commons is alleged to possess better taste than any one of its members. Our modern attitude is partly fatalism, but it is partly religious faith. A second science may be thought of, which deals 1 Compare Mr. Mallock's definition of evolution as " the reasonable sequence of the unintended " (Aristocracy and Evolution, p. 97), quoted in our closing chapter. 4 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD CHAP. with the objective and involuntary tendencies of social conduct — economics or political economy. This was on the ground before modern sociology, and Comte, who gave the latter science its name and claimed to be its author, regarded economics as a fragment of social science, wrongly studied in isola- tion from the rest, and therefore resulting in mistaken practical conclusions. In point of fact, one of the great difficulties or ambiguities of sociology arises no less plainly in economics. How make the transi- tion from study of facts to maxims for conduct ? In other words, is political economy an art or a science ? The accepted view nowadays regards political econ- omy as a science — the science of wealth ; and in spite of Comte' s protest, it is recognised as a distinct science, independent, in a sense, of sociology ; and that, mainly -because more definite conclusions are possible in regard to wealth than in regard to the wider social interests of mankind. On the other hand, it is fully recognised that, if you wish to frame maxims for conduct, you have to take much into account besides the economic tendencies of action. And it is also confessed that in its " palmy days " political economy had identified itself with a system of individualism — with a hard doctrine of individual rights, more especially rights of property — which may well be thought a menace to the public interests. Nevertheless — such is the irony of circumstances! — practically the same system has reappeared in all its stringency in the form of Mr. Herbert Spencer's sociology. Thirdly : Professor Mackenzie's Introduction to Social Philosophy adds another distinction — that of I INTRODUCTORY 5 social philosophy in contrast with social science. Sociology claims to rank as a science ; Mr. Macken- zie, who is entitled to respect, both on his own ac- count and as representing generally the position of the great Hegelian or Idealist school, conceives that there are philosophical positions presupposed in social science which need separate discussion. In consequence or partly in consequence of this, Mr. Mackenzie's book does not aim at giving us a body of social doctrines, but at vindicating on philosophi- cal grounds what he regards as wholesome social principles. The main significance of this, we think, is as follows, that, in contrast with the school which seeks to reduce social well-being to a problem in science, in analogy as far as may be to physical science and in close connection with it, there is an- other school, not less attached to a doctrine of cor- porate well or ill, which finds the highest authority in regard to human conduct in metaphysics. Fourthly : We might speak of the relation of sociology to ethics. But here the floods threaten to break loose and drown us. Here we come face to face with the question already mentioned — the ques- tion of the transition from science to art; from noting how things happen to declaring how they ought to happen. Without enlarging further upon that topic at this stage in our discussion, we may at least call attention to the fact that historically there has been a very close kinship between sociology and ethics. Their problem is almost, if not altogether, the same; the answer formulated is sometimes labelled "sociology," at other times "ethics," as on shipboard the jam is sometimes described as raspberry, some- 6 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD CHAP. times as plum, sometimes, it may be, as guava, yet in all you taste the monotonous flavour of apple, or of burnt sugar. Not less alike to each other are evolu- tionary ethics and evolutionary sociology. Thus — to anticipate for a moment — sociology was originally formulated by Comte as the true guide to conduct, the new authority, destined to supersede both ethics and religion. — He modified this position in later days, as we shall see, but only within limits, and at the out- set it was announced as we have given it. — Soci- ology offered to guide man with the help of biology ; society was an organism ; man was a member in the organism ; a part, not the whole ; essentially depend- ent on the whole, and bound to serve its interests. This conception reappears in Mr. Spencer ; he works out its suggestions in his own way, which is not Comte's ; but still he appeals to the analogy between society and an organism ; and he calls the discussion sociology. But when we turn to Mr. Leslie Stephen's Science of Ethics, we meet with identically the same discussion. True, Mr. Stephen prefers the expression "social tissue" to the expression " social organism," but the difference is essentially one of detail, and does not affect the question before us. We are still working the biological analogy, yet, if you please, this is ethics we are working at. The brand, no doubt, is different ; the liquor is the same. Spencer has elsewhere and in different form his discussion of ethics ; Stephen's ethics run parallel, not to Spencer's ethics, but to Spencer's sociology .> Again, Professor Alexander's Moral Order and Progress is, as the name implies, an ethical discussion, yet the author finds it impossible to discuss the problems of per- I INTRODUCTORY 7 sonal ethics apart from the relation of the individual to society, and his book is penetrated throughout with biological and evolutionary suggestions, most of all with the Darwinian struggle for existence. But such suggestions meet us at every hand in modern socio- logical discussions ; nay more, such suggestions it was the professed business of sociology to supple- ment and apply to human life. It is plain, therefore, that sociology and ethics, as sociologists generally conceive of sociology and of ethics, cannot be sepa- rated from each other. Some forms of ethical thought will wander far from the line of treatment proper to us in this essay. But, wherever you have these two things — an interpretation of duty as the debt which man, the individual, owes to society ; and secondly, the appeal to phenomenal fact as the only safe or real authority — there sociology and ethics must necessarily approach, intertwine, or even co- alesce. And therefore it would mutilate a study of sociological theories, not to include in our review those ethical systems which are plainly of the same house and lineage. Every argument proceeds upon certain assump- tions ; and it may be as well to confess at the outset what is to be assumed in the following essay, viz. the trustworthiness of the moral consciousness, or the reality of the distinction between right and wrong. This test will not be formally set aside, except by a few wild thinkers ; but it may be objected that assumptions ought to be vindicated, ought to be justified. Very true ; our test needs justification by philosophy, and we believe that philosophy can 8 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD CHAP. do the necessary work, but not here. We cannot incorporate en passant a body of metaphysical prole- gomena to ethics. We must be allowed to let our point of view stand as an assumption. Looking at matters thus, although we seek to learn from the theories reviewed, and especially from the interesting and valuable details which they have collected, yet our analysis will necessarily to a large extent be hostile. First, we ask whether the various theories agree with each other ? And on this Mr. Benjamin Kidd, himself a sociologist, tells us that sociologists are hopelessly divided in their attempts to furnish prac- tical guidance. The science was to have been founded by Comte fifty years ago and more ; Mr. Kidd seems to think it still needs founding by a new recurrence to biology. It is plain, therefore, that the appeal to fact has not yet done for the study of society what it promised to do. Neither theologians nor meta- physicians could have been more hopelessly at issue among themselves than the votaries of fact have been and still are. Secondly, we ask whether each author is so much as self -consistent ? Thirdly, we ask, granted that we learn some fresh truth, is it taught us authoritatively by science, whether by the science of biology or by some other ? or has natural science merely suggested parables to the moral judgment ? These formal or logical tests pretty well clear the ground. A remainder of our theories, however, is overthrown (fourthly) by the final test, by the touch- stone of the moral consciousness. Positively our argument can hardly be said to go beyond this point, that if biological clues are to afford I INTRODUCTORY 9 guidance for human conduct, they must be supple- mented by clearer moral and religious light, and in philosophy by some scheme of metaphysical evolu- tionism, marking a transition perhaps from " Darwin" to " Hegel." PART I COMTISM, WITH SOME SCATTERED PARALLELS CHAPTER II COMTE'S LIFE AND THE PRINCIPLES OF HIS TEACHING Comte as founder — His life — His books — The term " Sociology" — " Statics " (cf. Spencer) — " Dynamics " — Divisions of the Polity — Comte's religion — The term "Positive" — Four authorities superseded — Comte on psychology — And on ethics — Law of the three stages — Criticism — Transition to the study of Comte's relation to science — He repudiates dogmatic atheism and mate- rialism — His scale of values in the hierarchy of the sciences — Spencer's criticism ALONE perhaps of all sociologists, Comte may claim to have his life studied, however briefly, as an inte- gral part of the gospel he teaches. Auguste Comte was born at Montpellier in 1798. He was early distinguished for his mathematical ability ; also for a refractoriness to authority, which led to his expulsion from the Polytechnic School of Paris. In 1818 he met St. Simon the socialist, and became for six years his close friend and disciple ; but the alliance was broken off by a violent quarrel, never to be healed. In 1825 he married. The union proved conspicuously unhappy, and ended in a sepa- ration in 1842. In 1826 he began lectures upon his 10 CHAP, ii COMTE'S LIFE AND TEACHING 1 1 system of philosophy ; and though they were inter- rupted for a time by an attack of insanity, the lectures attracted great attention. Between 1830 and 1842 they were published in six volumes under the title of System of Positive Philosophy. While working for fame or usefulness by developing his system, Comte worked for bread and butter by the exercise of his mathematical talent, mainly in the service of that Polytechnic School from which he had been expelled in his student days. His eminence as a heresiarch cost him his connection with the school; and there- after he lived by his earnings as a private tutor, or by the gifts of his devoted disciples. In 1845 he became acquainted with his Egeria, a lady named Clo- thilde de Vaux, with whom he fell passionately in love, and to whom he looked back with passionate regret till his death in 1857, the lady having lived only one year after making acquaintance with Comte. There was no stain on their friendship, though it was the occasion of a good deal of folly upon Comte's part. In his later years, 1851-54, Comte published the second part or second form of his system, the Posi- tive Polity. We do not attempt to mention other works, but it is necessary to say something about the Philosophy and the Polity. The earlier treatise, the Philosophy, was an encyclopedia of scientific knowledge, as it then existed, crowned with the first rough sketch of the science of sociology. It was condensed in an English translation by Harriet Martineau, a transla- tion which was afterwards retranslated into French, as being an improvement upon Comte's own state- ment. This may be called our English tit-for-tat in 12 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI exchange for Dumont's relation to Bentham. The book was recently republished in English, when an able reviewer 1 protested against the absurdity of offering the reading public the science of fifty or sixty years ago. The Positive Polity, on the other hand, is sociology from beginning to end ; looking back, as we shall see, to the survey of the inferior sciences made in the Positive Philosophy, but work- ing out its own problems on the grand scale. ^ In the earlier book we have the two main divisions of sociology — first, social statics, or the conditions of social order ; these are treated briefly ; secondly, social dynamics, or the historical laws of social prog- ress in the past. All three names are somewhat singular. The name sociology — Comte's own coinage — is a hy- brid term, partly Latin and partly Greek. Social statics, again, is used in a different sense from that of Mr. Herbert Spencer's early treatise. With Spen- cer, social statics refers to a future Utopian period, when egoism and altruism are perfectly balanced ; a millennial age, when "that great disturbance of hu- man nature, which the churches call sin," has been left behind. It therefore corresponds to the " abso- lute ethics" or "ethics for the straight man" of Mr. Spencer's later system — a fresh proof, if further proof were needed, that ethics and sociology are only diverse names for the same product, as produc- tion is carried on in the schools of empirical sociol- ogy and evolutionary ethics. In the light of science it would seem that Comte's use of the phrase is much better justified than Spencer's. Mechanical statics 1 In the Manchester Guardian. CHAP, ii COMTE'S LIFE AND TEACHING 13 discuss the conditions of stability in actual life, not in some ideal world, where the properties of things have been modified out of all recognition. Lastly, the phrase social dynamics ought in accuracy to be social kinetics. By rights the name dynamics covers the whole field of mechanics, studying the conditions both of stability and of movement, and thus including as its two branches statics and kinetics. As for the name mechanics, it is usually extruded by men of science from the field of theory, and confined to prac- tice. However, the words dynamics and dynamical are so identified in sociological usage with that half of the subject which deals with motion, or, in other words, with historical change and growth, that it does not seem wise to attempt to disturb the inaccurate but well-established phraseology of tradition. The later book, the Polity, not only has a fuller discussion of sociology, but a greater number of topics or heads or subdivisions. First, there is a general sketch of Positivism. Secondly, there is an outline of the principles to be fully developed in what follows. Thirdly, there is an account of Social Stat- ics, i.e. of permanent conditions of social order ; very much fuller than in the Positive Philosophy, and therefore not merely naming or sketching in brief the Family, the State, and the Church or Human- ity, but treating the last specially at greater length, and adding discussions upon Language and upon Art. Fourthly, we have Social Dynamics, Comte's Philosophy of History. This had been given with disproportionate fulness in the early treatise ; but its discussion is a good deal enlarged in the later volume, though other points are still more enlarged. Lastly, 14 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI there is the Polity of the future, dogmatically detailed upon Positivist lines. It is plain that such a pro- gramme affords plenty of scope for repetition and reiteration. Comte makes full use of his opportuni- ties. We must remember that Comte had already in view the composition of the Polity when he issued his Philosophy. It is characteristic of the man to grind his few leading ideas round and round and round again in his own and in his reader's mind. A division or a generalisation is never expounded once for all ; we shall meet with it again as a subdivision in a different section. This is a failing which leans to virtue's side, but its scale is positively gigantic in Comte. Along with the difference in scale, and in precision of semi-political or legislative detail, there is to be noted a difference, up to a certain degree, in the animating spirit. Both treatises rely upon Comte's hierarchy of the sciences ; both rely upon his his- torical law of the Three Stages ; and both of them are affected by his belief that the heart ought to rule the head, or the intellect to be the servant of the affections. But the last point certainly counts for vastly more in the Polity than in the Philosophy. Between the date of the two treatises the church of humanity, as represented by its prophet Comte, had developed a whole system of worship. Some have regarded the two stages of Comte's thinking as flatly contradictory of each other. It seems better to recognise that, at every stage, there were diverse currents of thought or " streams of tendency " min- gling in Comte ; that he was perhaps divided against himself, habitually inconsistent, continuously self- CHAP. II COMTE'S LIFE AND TEACHING 1 5 contradictory. Certainly it is hard to reconcile the view that the heart is to be master of the intellect, and its result, the sentimental worship of Humanity, with the appeal to mere phenomenal fact. Yet Cerate and the Comtist elect are conscious of no self-contradiction. Both demands are merged in the blessed and magical word — Positive. What is it to be Positive ? In French, the word may have a special history, giving it a richer connota- tion. In English it has no such distinctive position ; it is merely the opposite of negative, or sometimes of natural, as when we contrast positive law with the obligations of natural law. Perhaps a combination of these two senses may suggest the Comtist view, especially if we can light up the result with an un- speakable glamour of love and complacency. Comte prefers positive historical institutions to what he regards as metaphysical dreams of natural law or natural rights. He prefers real facts to fictitious or ideal fancies. Yet the fictions had their use. They helped to clear away the mediaeval system, in doc- trine and polity, when it had grown obsolete. More than that the spirit of the Revolution — or, as Comte would say, the spirit of the Reformation and of the Revolution — could not possibly accomplish. But more is now demanded. That negative service has been done. We must be positive. Back then to the facts ; if we appeal to the right facts, in the right spirit, we shall positively save society ; positively, we shall ! The old authorities, whose defeat Comte usually takes for granted, were at least three or four in number. There was religion ; supernatural religion ; 16 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI what students call the positive religions of the world, claiming, many or most of them, to come by revela- tion. These had played their part in promoting human or social well-being during the theological stage of history, but they were long ago effete ; the metaphysical stage had superseded them, and it in turn was now yielding to the final or positive stage of knowledge. The other three authorities are all metaphysical, and on that ground are disowned by Comte ; metaphysics proper, the introspective method in psychology, and intuition. As it happened, these various alleged authorities had presented themselves in alliance to confront the assaults of modern Agnos- ticism ; and, as Comte believes, they had all been overthrown. The third, the introspective method in psychology, is perhaps not strictly an alleged guide to conduct ; but it stands in very close alliance with the fourth. If simple interrogation of consciousness teaches us truth in one great department of knowledge, Jen simple interrogation of the voice of conscience ay well be expected to teach us duty, and guide us fely in action. .''Comte, a more thorough-going ipiricist and phenomenalist than his English col- igues, the Mills and Spencers, is resolved to have nothing to do with the psychology of introspection. Psychology is either a department of physiology, phrenology perhaps; or, as he says in his later treatise, sociology is the true psychology, i.e. soci- ology gives us the one true doctrine of man. On the other hand, it was the earlier treatise which offered us sociology in lieu of ethics, — which, as we may say, carried its aversion to intuitionalism so far as to blot out of being the science which intuitional- CHAP, ii COMTE'S LIFE AND TEACHING 17 ism had so deeply infected. The later treatise rec- ognises that a science of morals ought to handle the problems of personal conduct, in the light of the conditions of social well-being established or defined by sociology. As being more complex, the discussion of personal duty in morals — a treatise which Comte never was able to compose — is placed by him later than sociology in his list of the sciences. Beyond this statement of his alleged Law of the Three Stages, Comte does not argue in favour of his agnostic background. He takes it over from his pred- ecessors in the business of speculation, empiricists and individualists of the ordinary type. Once he refers to Kant, telling us that Kant had had a very fair inkling of the biological view of human knowledge as a thing absolutely relative to its environment — being partly due to the activity of the organism, partly to the reaction of the environment ; the two elements mixing in a way that defies us to decompose them, and that forbids us to regard man as capable of pos- sessing absolute truth. But usually Comte is content to let history, as he understands history, tell its own tale. Once, mankind aspired to penetrate to the knowledge of causes. The race devoted itself to a theological interpretation of the world. First came Fetishism; every object in nature, every part of the mighty whole, was held to be alive, just as man him- self is alive. Unlike the writers of to-day, who gener- ally identify Fetishism with Animism — in the most approved sense of that slippery and misleading word — Comte has no intention of admitting that primitive mankind believed in spirits, temporarily or perma- nently connected with the Fetish. Not so; Comte 1 8 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI regards a belief in the soul as belonging to a much ore sophisticated state of mind than that of the 'amiable fetish worshippers, the first fathers of the human race. Not until the baleful shadow of meta- physics begins to fall upon human thought do we hear of souls in men, or of spirits in nature. To Comte, psychology is a kind of physiology ; psychical life is a property of the human body ; and, to the fetishist, psychical life was a property of the objects of nature. Again Comte differs from ordinary usage in extending the term fetish to cover any object in nature which might be worshipped — a river, a moun- tain, a star, the moon, the sun. By other writers, that highly ambiguous and arbitrary word is usually applied only to things which are or which may become private property. Fetishism, as understood by Comte, was regarded by him as the first form of religion. This, again, was part of the legacy to Comte of the Encyclopedists and their fellows. Out of Fetishism, according to Comte, grew Polytheism. The change is mainly attributed to the action of human reason. It came to be discovered that things which had been regarded as animated were really inanimate. But the theological delusion was not yet shaken off ; the human mind was not yet strong enough to go right on to the scientific or positivist consciousness. Instead of doing that, mankind invented a set of imaginary beings, called gods, lurking behind the phenomena of nature. To the gods were now attributed those activi- ties which observation would no longer suffer men to ascribe to stones or plants or unconscious natural forces. Next, out of Polytheism grew Monotheism. Here again reason had been at work; as the unity CHAP, ii COMTE'S LIFE AND TEACHING 19 and harmony of nature was more and more dis- covered, it became more and more difficult — at length it became impossible — to interpret the world as an effect produced by independent or rival agencies. There must be one great first cause ; one great man- like Being. Monotheism had begun; the last term in the theological development. But the develop- ment was to continue beyond Monotheism, and al- ready, unnoticed, under the dominance of the theo- logical stage, the germs of the metaphysical stage of mind were developing. \ Metaphysics, according to Comte, sees through the absurdity of belief in gods or in God ; reason is still active, and is very strongly impressed at this stage (says Comte) with the moral difficulties of Theism ; but, according to metaphy- sicians, all we have to do is to substitute abstractions for the discredited deities. In the metaphysical stage of thought we take these abstractions seriously, as if they could give a real and satisfying explanation of things; but they are only ghosts of causes, ghosts of gods, ghosts of the real living body under the style and title of souls, — and so forth and so forth. Drugs produce sleep because they have a soporific virtue. Life is due to some mysterious intangible vital energy. Chief of all the abstractions is Nature. Substitute / Nature for the monotheistic God and the feat is ac- complished ; the transition is made ; the first stage of thought has given place to the second. With the conception of nature grows up a crop of wild beliefs in natural laws — he means the jurist's natural law, not the physicist's — and in natural rights. These beliefs are powerful to destroy, powerless to create. But that is their use, — to clear away the rubbish and 2O FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART i debris of an obsolete intellectual and social order. Hence the reign of metaphysics must be incompara- bly shorter than the prevalence of the theological spirit. Already the new, the true, the final stage of thought was unfolding itself in a few rarely gifted minds. The one solid result of metaphysical inquiries consisted in the fragments of science accidentally dis- covered, either in antiquity or in the Middle Ages, by minds too finely touched for the metaphysical dreams which chiefly occupied them. In a sense, therefore, science antedated metaphysics. But more still, there must have been a leaven of positivism — i.e. of science — even in the earliest fetishist days, if human life was to be maintained on earth. And so we do not wonder to find that society was being built up, piece by piece, long before sociology was possible. In the days of fetishism the family was developed, — the most es- sential of all social formations. Polytheism, which ushered in the epoch of militarism, witnessed the construction of the State. At first, however, spiritual power and secular power were closely combined. Either the State was a Theocracy, in which the priests ruled; or in subsequent days the military classes, who had assumed command of the State, kept the priests under control. Both of these systems yielded very imperfect types of the State ; yet humanity owed much to them. The practical wisdom of the priests, and, still more, the sagacious instincts of secular statesmanship, did a great deal to counteract the anti- social tendencies of a developed theology. Instead of dreaming away their lives in religious joys, or in thoughts of another world — as their creeds may have demanded — men were disciplined by their wise rulers CHAP, ii COMTE'S LIFE AND TEACHING 21 to think of the interests of their country, and to aim at the public weal. Under Monotheism once more — i.e. under Christianity, or, as Comte calls it, " Catholi- cism " — a very great advance was made through the mediaeval separation of the spiritual and temporal powers. The empire of the German Caesars and the ecclesiastical Papacy stood over against each other in seemingly hostile array as competitors for the supreme place. Really, says Comte, the separation of theory from practice — for that is what it means from his point of view — was a decisive gain for human well- being. During the same epoch chivalry or defensive warfare formed a transition stage from the old aggres- sive militarism to the modern Industrialism. So much had already been wrought by the spirit of positivism, even before it had come to self-consciousness. But now science is fully accredited and well grown ; and industrialism, the definitive social order, which corre- sponds to science or positivism, the definitive stage of thought, lies all around us, albeit still in sad confusion. The long regency of God is at an end. The minority of Humanity has ceased. We are done with dreams of knowing the causes of things ; we are content henceforth to register sequences, and to calculate phenomena, for the practical ends of human welfare. Comte has appeared, and, by attending to his teaching, mankind now at last may enter the land of promise. Of course the value of this historical sketch of the progress of the human mind depends upon the degree in which it is true, and in which its truth can be demonstrated. It is hardly necessary to say that while it reveals wide knowledge and great power of generalisation, it also contains many assumptions, 22 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI and much prejudice, and not a little which is now proved to be false. The early history of human re- ligions and human institutions is still indeed extremely obscure. Many theories are put forward ; none can claim a complete victory. And yet it is not too much to say that Comte's neat little sketch of Fetishism, and its uses, and its successors, must be laid aside among the things which are curious but not service- able. However, the question specially before us at this moment is whether Comte's historical survey justifies his agnostic creed. In support of Comte there is one striking fact to be noticed. The field assigned to natural law has constantly tended to ex- pand; supernatural agency, even by those who believe in it, has been put farther and farther back, farther and farther off. So much Comte may certainly claim to have made good. But it is still matter for argu- ment whether this really points to the cessation of theological and metaphysical belief. The question is a metaphysical one, to be fought out on metaphysi- cal grounds. In his dislike and contempt for meta- physics, Comte offers us merely what one may call historical statistics of the dwindling of faith. But that is to postpone the question indefinitely. Till faith in God has died out like faith in witchcraft, history cannot claim to pronounce upon it a sentence of worthlessness. Or we may propose another issue. Let us consider Comte's appeal to science. If that works out so clearly and satisfactorily as to carry us unhesitatingly with it, then we may feel that Comte has justified his cavalier attitude towards those mighty allies, faith and reason. On the other hand, if Comte's positive CHAP, ii COMTE'S LIFE AND TEACHING 23 construction fails to commend itself, we shall be justified in " considering yet again " the old-fashioned guides to truth and duty, for which sociology was to be a substitute. Now, first, we must remark that Comte does not absolutely shut the door against faith. While he re- gards belief in a God as the second-last outworn raiment of human thought, he declines with some in- dignation to be called an atheist. God, say his disciples, may or may not exist; the question lies beyond the competency of human reason to settle. So, too, the doctrine of a soul separate from the body is assigned by Comte to the last outworn phase of thought — the metaphysical. Yet, if you call Comte a materialist, his facile indignation once more over- flows. He belongs, therefore, to the agnostic group. He will neither say " yes " nor " no." But he is filled with scorn for those who say "yes," for he is perfectly and dogmatically assured that we have no right to dogmatise. Moreover, his attitude towards the claims of his rivals looks very differently in dif- ferent sentences or paragraphs. When he denounces the dreams of theories that transgress the limits of human reason, he speaks in the tone of one who possesses real knowledge through the positive sci- ences. But, when he explains that mankind is abandoning inquiry into causes, it forces itself with a shock upon the reader's mind that the opposite is the case. It is knowledge that we are surrendering. It is reality that we are forsaking. Our predecessors may have failed to attain real knowledge. For argu- ment's sake take it, if you like, that they failed piti- ably. Still there is this to be said, they tried ; whereas 24 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI we, the crowning race, are to give up real knowledge, and to content ourselves with registering useful sequences. We have not awakened from a dream, but rather fallen from a dream into a stupor. This also is characteristic of the whole agnostic group. It is easy to write the words " limitation " or " relativity of knowledge " ; but is hard to work out your mean- ing so that this relativity or this adamantine limit shall not involve the abrogation 'and annihilation of knowledge. But those who despise metaphysics far too thoroughly to study it, will always be found rejoicing in scraps of metaphysical "creeds outworn." Next, we observe that, while Comte appeals to phenomenal fact and positive science, he does not place all sciences upon the same level. He has arranged them in a scale — ist, Mathematics (includ- ing Arithmetic, Algebra, Geometry, Mechanics); 2nd, Astronomy; 3rd, Physics (with subdivisions — Sound, Light, Heat, Electricity, etc.); 4th, Chemistry; 5th, Biology or Physiology; 6th, Sociology; to which the Positive Polity adds, 7th, Ethics. In the Positive Philosophy there is a full review of the state of know- ledge regarding the various branches of mathemati- cal and physical science at the time when Comte wrote. This order is regarded as the best order, the right order, the order chosen by the />ow/-to9, the wise and well-cultured man, Auguste Comte. It is not simply an order of initial ease and progressive diffi- culty. It is mainly an order for study — roughly coinciding with the order of discovery — but princi- pally justified by the statement that each science presupposes the results of its predecessors, while it CHAP. II COMTE'S LIFE AND TEACHING 2 5 marks out for itself a new field of scientific achieve- ment by detecting new uniformities. Before Comte, it is urged, there was no science of society. Comte learned from biology to regard society as an organ- ism, profoundly related to its environment. But that did not establish a science of sociology. Two lumi- nous generalisations did so — the Law of the Three Stages, and the Hierarchy of the Sciences. This illustrates to us the intricate arrangement of material characteristic of Comte's redundant method. The Hierarchy of the Sciences includes sociology ; but again, the hierarchy is revealed to mankind by soci- ology ; and, once more, the hierarchy constitutes one- half the title-deeds of sociology, justifying its claim to be ranked with the sciences. It is a somewhat remarkable development of phe- nomenalism, this arrangement of sciences, not merely in sequence but in a rising scale. It recalls to mind the great Idealist systems of Germany, so like, and so unlike, Comte's philosophy. One is not surprised to find Spencer protesting against the ladder of know- ledge, — protesting that the relation between different sciences is not one of superiority and subordination, but one of equal reciprocity, each borrowing from each, each lending to the other. Still, if only be- cause, as Carlyle said, " speech is linear though char- acter is solid," — still, it is necessary to take sciences one at a time, — first one, then another; the synthetic philosophy itself has a beginning, a middle, and an end. And probably Comte's view has better justi- fication than Spencer's, though there is a measure of truth in each. It is true that borrowing and lending go on between different sciences, backwards and for- 26 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI wards, up and down ; but it is also true — and the truth is of greater importance — that high branches of science are dependent on the results of lower and simpler branches. In spite of the prejudices of phe- nomenalism, a scale of values will assert itself as we deal with the different branches of human knowledge. Of course Comte had his own explanation of the origin of this scale of values. It is purely subjective, a matter of human convenience. To take things in this order suits us, and therefore we rightly do so ; for intellectual curiosity is always to be kept in subordination to the claims of the affections. But how does it happen that human knowledge, upon the whole, lends obedience to the demands of the moral nature ? How is it that knowledge comes to us, imperfectly but really, in the form of a system, where the later parts imply the previous parts and carry us further on ? In other words, how comes it that our subjective synthesis does not distort the knowledge which phenomena afford, but rather brings out its inner meaning ? Comte is in a curious half- way position between phenomenalism, to which one fact is as good as another, and idealism, to which knowledge is a thing that objectively and really grades itself. It is a thin disguise of intellectual helplessness when Comte asserts that we have such a grouping of phenomena in our knowledge, but that the grouping is due merely to man's capricious regard for the interests of his own species. "Facts are chiels that winna ding." They are not so easily manipulated as Comte implies. Putting the matter in our own way, we may say that Comte' s positive and constructive teaching CHAP, ii COMTE'S LIFE AND TEACHING 27 has three sources of light and leading, in which it trusts — (1) The appeal to Biology. (2) The appeal to History. (3) The doctrine of Altruism. We shall say a few words about each in turn. CHAPTER III THE APPEAL TO BIOLOGY The "social organism" in other writers — In Comte — Idealist supple- ment to the biological appeal — Professor Mackenzie's statement of the idealist view — Intuitionalist criticism of the appeal — Comte uses a biological parable — Consistent phenomenalism means (if not evolutionism) hedonism — Comtism and hedonism two half truths [Note A. On Drummond's Natural Law in the Spiritual World — "Biological religion," according to Finlayson — Drummond ap- peals to biogenesis — His religion is Calvinistic, rather, or Gnostic — His noble zeal for continuity in knowledge] BIOLOGY comes next below sociology in Comte's scheme of the sciences. As we have seen, it is some- what difficult to know how far, upon Comte's own principles, this juxtaposition of the two sciences war- rants him in expecting the ideas of the lower science to serve as a guiding clue in the construction of the higher. Let it be enough to say that, whether in obe- dience to his own principles or without warrant from them, Comte has drawn a good deal from the biologi- cal analogy. As far back in time as the secession of the Roman Plebs, the parable of the " belly and the members " is alleged to have taught moral lessons to hot-headed or selfish factions. Again, in St. Paul's account of the Church, we are introduced to an or- ganism in which all the members rejoice or suffer 28 CHAP, in THE APPEAL TO BIOLOGY 29 together, sympathising fully with one another. It is an extension of the Christian spirit which leads modern thinkers to apply the same image to the State or to civil society. The contrast has been tellingly drawn between St. Paul's appeal as to a well-known fact — "Ye are members one of another" — and the Greek despair of being able to name any authority strong enough to overrule personal selfish- ness. When modern thinkers call society an organ- ism, they say in effect, not merely to fellow-Christians, but to fellow-citizens or fellow-men, " We are mem- bers one of another;" they say it, counting on a response ; and they obtain not a little response, thanks to the spread of the Christian spirit and Christian ethic. Moreover, science takes up the keynote in such a phrase as " the physiological di- vision of labour," a phrase which shows us how the lower science is at times indebted for suggestions to a higher — in this instance, physiology, to the eco- nomic branch of the science of society — but which also shows us the reality and the scientific service- ableness of the analogy between the two fields of study. Apparently Comte himself was aware that biology and sociology in some respects formed a class to- gether, contrasting with the lower sciences. In his little book on Comte, Dr. Edward Caird twice over l tells us that Comte recognised even in biology, much more in sociology, the necessity of bringing to a focus that esprit dy ensemble for which he pleads, and for explaining the parts by their place and function in the whole, not the whole by the co-operation of 1 2nd edition, pp. 61, 132. 3O FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI mutually independent parts. This spirit grew on Comte more and more. " Humanity," he said at last, "is alone real; the individual is an abstraction." In so far as he appealed to biology for encourage- ment in such teaching, Comte was following biologi- cal clues in the new science of sociology. Now, if this be so, an adherent of the German idealism will welcome Comte's progress, such as it is. He will think it far better to expound human reason — and what he regards as a creation of human reason, human society — in terms of biology rather than in terms of mechanism, or of " matter and motion." Neither interpretation may be adequate, but Comte's will seem to the idealist much nearer the truth than the other. Only the idealist will lament that the scale of the sciences is cut off with a knife at biology. He thinks life a truer, richer, fuller, worthier cate- gory than affinity or force, or any purely physical conception ; but he believes there is a higher cate- gory still, viz. self-conscious reason. He believes that, while the processes of life may do a good deal to throw light upon the processes of reason, the pro- cesses of reason throw back even more light upon the allied yet inferior processes studied by physi- ology. The idealist holds that reason has gone to the making of all things ; that it shows a little of itself in the lower sciences, much of itself in the sciences of biology and physiology, but all of itself in self-consciousness — self-consciousness, which is the open secret of the world, and which does not need to be studied at second hand either in biology or in sociology when we can study it in itself, and in its workings everywhere. Good to use CHAP, in THE APPEAL TO BIOLOGY 3 1 biology as a help, says the idealist ; but why stop at biology ? 1 It is perhaps the same position in different words when Mr. Mackenzie tells us that his doctrine of an organism (as applied to the social organism) is a meta- physical category. The perfect realisation of unity in difference, the whole in all the parts, each for all, and all for each, is only hinted in natural organisms, but is achieved in the life of reason and of goodness. Men of science need not trouble to tell idealists of supposed errors in the idealist conception of an organism. Idealist philosophers go to science for hints, for rough outline sketches, for parables ; it is to reason they apply for final and authoritative reve- lations. Few animal organisms may display any perfect relativity of the whole to the parts, and of the parts to the whole. If you cut off my head I die. If you cut off my arm, unless you do it very clumsily, I do not die. The head therefore seems to be a necessary and integral element in the organism ; the arm does not. Or, again, if a lobster loses a claw he can grow another. I, alas ! may lose a leg or an arm, and still survive, but I cannot replace the miss- ing limb. Is the lobster the truer and worthier organism? It cannot do without any one part, and if any part goes amissing, what has been lost is reproduced by the remainder of the organism. Or an organism which, so to speak, was all heads, would seem to be a metaphysically perfect or beau-ideal organism, where every part was vitally necessary, 1With an interesting and characteristic modification, Professor Baldwin of Princeton affirms that Psychology gives us the true clue to the nature of society. 32 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART i because each part was implied in all the rest. The human organism, happily for us, does not illustrate the metaphysical category in this phase of perfec- tion. Yet the category is not irrelevant. In the healing of a wound physiologists recognise some- thing analogous to the mysterious power by which the lobster grows a fresh claw. Thus the parable ex- ists in nature, but the fulfilment is found in reason and in conscience. Far more fully than any members in one of nature's organisms, "we" — human beings, God's children — " are members one of another." Our mutual dependence is absolute ; our life, if torn as- under from each other, is no human life at all. A different criticism might be stated by one believ- ing lesa/confidently than idealists do in the completed . scale/of the sciences, while attaching more distinctive importance than they attach to the revelations of the >moral consciousness. Such a one would ask, Is this *-^ biological parable anything more than a covert appeal to the moral consciousness ? Is it anything more than a fantastic way of saying, " You ought," a masked transition from the " So it is " of phenome- nalism to the " So it ought to be " of ethics ? Reli- gion, at least in its historical forms, has been deposed ; Christianity has been scouted ; intuition has been laughed down ; philosophy has been told to vanish with the ghosts before the noontide of science. Yes, but how are you going to bring men under authority when so many authorities have been sent packing ? It is very convenient if you can assert the claim, the moral claim, of the community in the par- able of body and members ! This may not be a perfect moral authority, but it is at any rate an CHAP, in THE APPEAL TO BIOLOGY 33 authority, and in the bankruptcy of the moral con- sciousness any authority is better than none. Nay, for Comte it is the very authority he wants, human and governmental. Yet this doctrine of the social organism is no pronouncement in the name of facts ; it is a moral dictum, picturesquely stated in terms of popular science. The community is doubtless part of the moral authority to which each man owes allegiance. But the parable of the social organism would not win the wide acceptance it does if it were not for the authority of conscience within, and for the training of conscience by the authority of the Christian spirit during centuries. We conclude then that the appeal to biology has done Comte a very great service. After he had cut away the foundation of morals he has been able to find a new foundation in the tacit assumption that individual men are bound to the service of the com- mon weal ; and this assumption is masked, and made to look like the statement of a scientific fact, by the process of borrowing a parable from biology. Of course it may be rejoined that Comte is much more true to his phenomenalist assumptions, and that he is merely appealing to fact when he uses the bio- logical parable. Any one, it may be said, can see that men are dependent upon society, and that selfishness leads to unhappiness, not to happiness. That, how- ever, suggests hedonism, and hedonism is strange to Comte. Hedonism represents the earlier and probably the more consistent working out of a phe- nomenalist view of human conduct ; but sociology represents a strong reaction from it, as from other manifestations of individualism. Probably it will be 34 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI admitted to-day in most quarters that J. S. Mill failed logically in his generous attempt to establish the claims of all upon the fact of each man's personal interest in his own happiness. Some more recent sociological schools do indeed resume the appeal to hedonism ; but they do so — as we shall shortly note — in connection with a doctrine of evolution which was unknown to Comte, and which those who rely on it regard as affording a new basis for morals, a new rampart against the assaults of a destructive individualism. To unsophisticated phenomenalism, one fact is as good as another ; and there is no fact more pressing than the claims of self. It may pos- sibly be argued that the new doctrines of evolution bridle the spirit of selfishness by showing that each individual inherits a sort of compendium of the moral experience of past ages. But, at any rate, in the absence of evolutionary doctrine, Comte had to qual- ify or corrupt his phenomenalism in the interests of the public weal. It is not because experience proves society to be the true source of individual happiness that Comte champions society, or that he sings the praises of the social life. He ignores our specifically human experience, and assimilates man's life, as far as possible, to natural or animal existence. He will not admit that reason has disintegrated the purely instinctive co-operation of gregarious animals, so that it can never be reconstituted. And he has no vision of a higher fellowship, created only by the rational and moral nature of man, or by that glorious Nature whose image is borne by man alone, of all creatures upon earth. Comte has his psychology of the rational nature, — of its characteristic selfishness CHAP, in THE APPEAL TO BIOLOGY 35 and its no less characteristic unselfishness ; but his doctrine, as we shall see, is profoundly unsatisfac- tory, and his appeal to biology is a counsel of despair. Instead of saying, " On to the fuller development of reason and goodness, for the cure of the ills under which we groan," Comte says rather, " Back to the life of sense, in which these ills had not yet emerged." Comtism ignores the idiosyncrasy of man as a ra- tional being ; hedonism at any rate recognises it in however perverted a form. We must seek to attain some worthier recognition of the great fact. Biology is indeed a parable of the moral life, but still it is only a parable. The resemblances are counterpoised by immense differences. When these differences are neglected an appeal to biology in the interest of morals becomes a piece of mere improved assumption. And Comte is more dependent on this appeal than he ever clearly admits. He is more dependent on it than his principles quite warrant. The only fashion in which Comte is able to say " You ought " is in the formula, " Society is an organism." Other sociologists have other reasons for making the appeal to biology ; it stands for this in Comte. And there- fore this appeal in Comte is not a scientific state- ment of fact, but rather, a rudimentary and defective form of the moral judgment, — valuable, no doubt, but valuable upon the principle which makes the one-eyed man king of the blind. NOTE A. On "Natural Law in the Spiritual World" [The appeal to biology has been traced in a dif- ferent quarter, in the lamented Henry Drummond's 36 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI first and brilliantly successful book, Natural Law in the Spiritual World. This book was criticised in a pamphlet under the name of Biological Religion, by one less widely known, but not less deeply loved in life or lamented in death, Dr. Finlayson.1 Drum- mond of course appeals to the sharp modern doctrine of biogenesis, with its denial of all forms of sponta- neous generation or xenogenesis ; with its assertion of life from life, and like from like. It is certainly curi- ous that an age which has taken stock so heavily in evolutionary speculations — and the very men of science who were pioneers in evolution and popular- isers of its results — should also have reaffirmed, on the ground of fresh experiments, a view of life closely associated with creationist doctrines. Drummond, for one, appeals in his early work to biological science, because he is a theological creationist. His analogy is somewhat wire-drawn; his biology is of the simplest, rarely going beyond the single point named ; when it does go further, as in discussing Degeneration or Parasitism, still extremely simple, and not very consistent with the foundation doctrine of biogenesis. The book really offers us Neo- Calvinist religion, or even Neo-Gnostic, more truly than biological religion ; but it shows the same con- tempt for metaphysics and the same blind confidence in empirical science which distinguish Comte and many lesser sceptics. Its religious teaching is often admirable, but the parable on which it is built mis- leads the author, because he supposes it to be more than a parable. Intellectually, the best feature in the book is the determination to trace continuity 1 The late minister of Rusholme Congregational Church, Manchester. CHAP, in THE APPEAL TO BIOLOGY 37 between different worlds of thought. This effort reappears in Drummond's later book, The Ascent of Man, of which we may have something to say here- after. Otherwise, the later treatise is largely an in- version of the previous one. It obliterates the theological discontinuousness between the natural and the spiritual man, which had been so strangely supported by the assertion that the laws of physical nature must be viewed as continuous and operative in all regions of experience, even the most spiritual.] CHAPTER IV THE APPEAL TO HISTORY In Dr. Hatch — Criticism — In Ritschl, how far Comtist — Other ap- peals ; to historic parallels — Example from Comte — To the whole tendency of history — More usual in Comte ; examples — Criticism — Mr. Mackenzie's criticism — Guidance to be gained from history is limited — Comte's varied and capricious appeals to it To appeal to history for guidance is a very natural resource on the part of those who distrust philosophy. It is found even among theologians who are inter- ested, as Comte was not, in preserving belief in God. Probably the appeal was never made with more clearness or with more confidence than by Dr. Edwin Hatch in his St. Giles Lecture, "From Metaphysics to History." * Dr. Hatch can find no language in which to express his contempt for metaphysics, or his confidence in modern physical science. "We have passed into a new atmosphere. We have around us, not the glamour of a splendid mist, but the light of day." Science has " passed from metaphys- ics to fact, and" has "passed thereby from doubt to certainty." One province remains to be liberated — that of theology. Let us make a similar transition here, " from metaphysics to history " ; then, even in theology, we shall find solid ground below our feet. The history which Dr. Hatch has in view is history of 1 Published in the Contemporary Review for June, 1889. 38 ' CHAP, iv THE APPEAL TO HISTORY 39 doctrine, the history of theological beliefs. If we treat these in the light of the comparative method they will no longer be meaningless, but meaningful ; we may even discover that " God is not only reveal- ing Himself to His creatures, but also realising Him- self to Himself " in history. There is a great deal that is Comtist in this pro- gramme. To " abandon the search for essences and look only to the operation of forces " is thoroughly Comtist in spirit, though even " forces " is too meta- physical a term for Comte's taste ; he would write " sequences." The result contemplated, no doubt, is anything but Comtist; but how immense the gulf between the method recommended and the results desired ! Either our Theistic beliefs are valid and defensible ; but, if so, there are other fields of know- ledge besides that cultivated by phenomenal science, and other methods of study for metempirical and metaphysical subjects. Or else Theism is merely a human delusion ; but, if so, historical science can do nothing to galvanise it into fresh life. The sum of the longest series of cyphers is still zero. In one thing Dr. Hatch is right. Our age is pre-eminently an age of historical study. Very likely our age does better work in dealing with the history of beliefs, theological or other, than in dealing directly with the problem of their justification. Nay, our age may even make its best contributions to metaphysics or theology at second hand in the regions of history. But, if so, that is the weakness of our age, not its strength. And, in any case, profitable treatment of the history of such opinions implies a belief that they deal with facts, not hallucinations. Few of us, 40 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI indeed, may be so metaphysical as Dr. Hatch. A strange way surely of banishing metaphysics, to pro- pose construing God's realisation of Himself to Him- self! The greatest idealists, with Hegel at their head, could not have improved on that programme. Dr. Hatch appealed to the history of doctrine ; it is in a different sense that the modern German theolo- gians, to whom he stood nearest, make this appeal "from metaphysics to history." Ritschl and his school have mainly in view one race of mankind, and one epoch of time. They believe that, in the course of human history, truths have emerged and forces re- vealed themselves which satisfy human longings and lead human thought to its highest attainments. It is not merely history as a general survey of human de- velopment which they prize, but that history whose centre is Jesus Christ. Finding in history a revelation of Himself by God, they are able to honour history as the one true light of men. Otherwise unknown, God has here manifested Himself; otherwise un- blessed, mankind here attains to happiness and salva- tion. Of course this sharply cut conception of revelation and its limits gives rise to very grave diffi- culties ; but, amid all these, the appeal to history as urged by Ritschl has a seriousness and a significance which we cannot allow to Dr. Hatch's light-hearted paragraphs. So far, there appears no kind of affinity between the Ritschl school and Comtism. Yet there are many symptoms of relationship, and we find traces of them even in the matter now under discussion, — even in relation to the appeal to history. Much of the significance of Ritschl's appeal to history lies in CHAP, iv THE APPEAL TO HISTORY 41 the repudiation of the claim of physical science to rank as an authority in the spiritual life of man. Nature, according to Kaftan, is to be interpreted by history, not history by nature. As a progressive spiritual being, reaching his full stature under Christian influ- ences, man claims that he shall not ultimately be made subject to the forces of blind and unprogressive nature ; he cries out for God to rescue the historical gains of human culture and human faith from the de- structive forces of the natural world ; he finds God answering or anticipating his cry in Jesus Christ. There is nothing like this in Hatch. With him history scarcely differs from a new department of physical science. But we observe a manifest parallel between this Ritschlian position and Comte's subjec- tive synthesis or subordination of the head to the heart. At the same time, there are immense differ- ences. Justifiably or unjustifiably, the Ritschl school, amid all their scorn for dogmatic metaphysics, be- lieve that they themselves, in their own way, have verified faith in God. They think that they have saved theology from the wreck of opinions, by stating it as a view of the contents of historical revelation, and as vouched for by its correspondence with man's nature and needs. In Comtism the subjective or affectional synthesis is admittedly a piece of human make-believe. Objectively corresponding to it, there is — nothing. But how does Comtism itself, which has dismissed all interest in theology and all belief in God, make its own appeal to history for social guidance ? Or in what different ways may such an appeal be made, purely in the interests of society ? 42 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI The simplest view that can be taken is that which regards history as " philosophy teaching by ex- amples." This view has been eagerly pressed upon our generation by one of its most brilliant teachers, Sir J. R. Seeley, though with a special reference to politics in the stricter sense, rather than to what we distinguish as social problems. Political history, ac- cording to Seeley, gives us the politics of the past, while present-day politics are, to the statesman of wide views, history in the making. All manner of experi- ments in living, some of them successful and others unsuccessful, are recorded in the book of history. We moderns, with so immense a volume to study, ought to be safeguarded against many errors; and we ought to find ourselves in possession of many pieces of practical wisdom, not as discoverers but as heirs. Now Comte sometimes falls back upon the teach- ing of history in this simple and obvious sense. For example, he demands that the modern nation state should be broken up, under the positivist regime of the future, into fragments not much greater than the city states of antiquity. He allots to each a popula- tion of from one to three millions, the population of a great city, or of a canton or province of moderate dimensions. And he gives as his reason the teaching of experience, which is said to show that tyranny in- variably sets in when larger aggregates are massed together in one political organisation. The assertion perhaps may startle us, but, true or false, it is an appeal to history, and an appeal to history in the obvious sense, in which history is regarded as a col- lection of examples or of experiments in living. CHAP, iv THE APPEAL TO HISTORY 43 Oftener, however, Comte treats history in a differ- ent fashion. He would agree with J. S. Mill,1 that, in contrast with the physical sciences, history dis- closes a law, not of repetition, but of continuous progressive development. Mill is careful to guard himself against making any assumption in this defini- tion as to the moral value of one stage in history when compared with another. Progress in the moral sense he does not affirm ; he affirms merely the technical law that the curve which describes the course of history never returns upon itself. This belief is one of the characteristic differences between the East and the West and between antiquity and the modern world. The whole of oriental mankind, with all its sages and all its faiths, believes in the doctrine that history repeats itself. It is part of the burden of the bitter book of Ecclesiastes in Old Testament Scripture ; after immense labour, we find ourselves again exactly where we stood long ago. Even in the West, the same doctrine was largely held in classical times. Perhaps in the modern West — in the Chris- tian or semi- Christian West — we too easily make the transition from asserting progress in the intellectual sense, as a continuous evolution of change from change, novelty from novelty, to asserting progress in the moral sense, as continuous improvement. Per- sonally, no doubt, Mill himself believed in moral progress as firmly as in continuous historical change. And Comte believed both — the intellectual no less than the moral : " as if," he cries, " history ever repeated itself." But, if history does not repeat itself, the past cannot furnish examples to the present. 1 In his Logic, and elsewhere. 44 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI If we are to learn from the past it must be mainly in some other way. Shall we say then that we are to ascertain from historical study which causes are gaming and which declining ? And thereafter are we to shout with the biggest crowd ? Is the teaching of history to be a grandiose contribution to our study of the question which way the cat jumps ? Comte's Law of the Three Stages — an alleged continuous evolution in the history of the past — may be so interpreted ; it may be taken as a warning not to commit ourselves to modes of belief which are plainly growing obso- lete. And it may be urged that, under due restric- tions, there is high wisdom, not ignoble policy, in bowing to the declared and inevitable forces of his- tory. Burke has given classical utterance to this position in well-known words. " If a great change is to be made in human affairs, the minds of men will be fitted to it ; the general opinions and feelings will draw that way. Every fear, every hope will forward it, and then they who persist in opposing this mighty current in human affairs will appear rather to resist the decrees of Providence itself than the mere designs of men." It is this master current of tendency which we are to think of as the Zeitgeist. The name is not to be profaned, as one may say, by applying it to every little ripple upon the surface of events. Mr. Disraeli, presenting himself before the students of Glasgow University as a wise and good old man, felt all his wonted dramatic relish of the game of life in his new part of Lord Rector, when he told his young hearers that they must clearly un- derstand the spirit of their age ; perhaps they would CHAP, iv THE APPEAL TO HISTORY 45 feel themselves called to serve it, perhaps to thwart it; but in any case it must be understood. Such counsels assume that we mean by the Zeitgeist paltry and sectional movements of mind. But if we define the Zeitgeist in a limited and honorific sense, resist- ance to the master principle of an age comes peril- ously near to fighting against God. In this sense some younger students of sociology have deliberately suggested that one ought to learn from history in what line things are moving, and then to help the movement with all one's powers. But here very grave difficulties suggest themselves. If the unconscious reason of things knows in which direction to move, presumably it also knows where to stop, which is no less important. When the first railway tubular bridges were erected — the Britannia Bridge over the Menai Straits, the Victoria Bridge at Montreal — they were made much heavier than has been found necessary in the light of fuller knowledge. What should we say of the wiseacre who proposed to carry out the principle 'of lightening railway bridges by constructing them of lace or gossamer ? In ma- terial affairs such proposals are never made. One glance would show their absurdity. But as mankind, especially in an age of prevailing agnosticism, stum- ble hither and thither in search of social guidance, no absurdity is too crude to find supporters ; and many a tendency which was good within limits is urged upon us without any limit as the plain teach- ing of history. We have recently emerged, or are emerging, from a period of emancipating legislation, in which unwise or obsolete laws have been abolished, and individual freedom has grown wider. The ten- 46 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI dency was doubtless good within limits ; but does this fact constitute any presumption whatever in favour of the anarchist, revolutionary or philosophi- cal, who bids us entirely abolish organised govern- ment, and promises in return a golden age of perfect happiness ? The mere fact that a policy was wise or was inevitable up till now is no proof that it ought to be further persevered in. The surgeon may have removed first a finger, then the hand, then the fore- arm, as he found gangrene appearing and reappear- ing ; but that is no reason whatever for operating at the shoulder if the upper arm is healthy. Again, we may quote Mr. Mackenzie's statement of the objections to the policy under discussion, — the policy of pushing on along the lines where nature or history has shown us the way. If we could be certain of distinguishing the master tendency of an age from the crowd of rival tendencies in which it is all but lost, then history might be a sufficient guide. But too often, says Mr. Mackenzie, reflection becomes conscious of a social maxim only when the maxim is overripe, when it is ceasing to be healthy, or even to be completely alive. And so the conscientious stu- dent is apt to prolong the tendencies of the recent past rather than to detect the true needs of the pres- ent or the tendencies of the immediate future. He exhibits the weakness of the doctrinaire. The prac- .tical man, who is in touch with reality, though only half conscious of the principles and reasons why his policy is the right one, is more truly scientific than his pretentious critic in the arm-chair. When all men contribute to build a prophet's tomb, one may shrewdly conjecture that his message is no longer CHAP, iv THE APPEAL TO HISTORY 47 piercing and discomforting the conscience of the age. When impracticable politicians form a league for the defence, not of property only, but of liberty, one may fairly conclude that liberty is in no special danger, but that other interests of the commonwealth, not less vital to it, had best be looked to. It would appear, then, that history cannot guide us very securely. It cannot guide us by quoting par- allels from its repertory, for it is very hard to say what is a parallel ; and it cannot guide us by disclosing what is the master tendency of the present age, for such tendencies are seldom recognised in time. If history makes us wise, our wisdom arrives too gener- ally after the event. Nevertheless, the study of his- tory will be more and more imperative on all those who wish to counsel their fellows. It is mere waste of faculty to ignore the experience of the past, so far as that experience is available. Historical culture will give a man breadth of view. It will lead him to distrust sweeping generalisations and a priori formu- las. It will teach him that every institution and method is relative to the social state of those by whom it is practised. But he who is to lead men strongly must draw wisdom from some other and higher source. History can give secondary elements of guidance ; primary elements it cannot give. And there will always be the danger which that austerest of libre penseurs Mr. John Morley has emphasised, the danger that the historic method may justify any- thing in its own time, everything in its own place, and may relegate to limbo the distinction between right and wrong. Right and wrong — history illus- trates that great polar contrast, but cannot fully 48 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI teach it; yet after all is not that the beginning of wisdom ? And is it not very nearly the end of wis- dom too ? A last word must be added upon Comte's own use of the appeal to history, out of which so much of his sociological writing is composed. On the whole, he seems to owe a smaller definite debt to history than to biology. Sometimes he appeals to examples, as in the case quoted, when he refers tyranny to the undue size of the state. Sometimes he appeals to the past stream of tendency, as in his great generalisation of the three stages. Sometimes again he cuts right across the stream of manifest tendency ; he surely does this in demanding that the large and organic modern state should be divided up into fragments ; and in general no charge would seem to be more clearly made out than that Comte scarcely tries to shows us his polity for the future growing out of the life of the past. Sometimes he appeals to a historical phenomenon, like the division of the spiritual and secular powers, which has struck his fancy. In such a case history is like a great magazine of wares, and Comte is like a purchaser strolling through it, who puts down upon his list of household requirements — and Comte is catering for the household of humanity — anything which pleases his own taste. History is here the source of suggestions, and, as Comte has much his- torical learning, he has a wealth of suggestions at his command ; but history to him is certainly not a ruler or a judge. On the whole, Comte practises the ap- peal to history with very little seriousness. The pre- dominant partner in his lawgiving is the subjectivity of Auguste Comte, CHAPTER V THE DOCTRINE OF ALTRUISM A fragment of ethics — On a psychological basis — Opposes psychologi- cal hedonism — Healthily, but incompetently — Fitzjames Ste- phen's objection to it ; we cannot alter nature's forces! — That is good determinism but bad morals — Ethically, is a new conception of virtue — Scientifically worthless [Mr. Baldwin] — " Balance " is preferred to altruism by Butler at times — By Spencer — Criticism A THIRD practical or moral authority is found by Comte in the doctrine of Altruism. Vivre pour autrui is to be our constant inspiration and our shin- ing goal. This is really a fragment of that ethical portion of his system which Comte did not live to work out. The definition of Altruism is never formulated ; it is never supported in argument ; it is merely taken for granted. None the less it exerts an immense influence in Comte's own system, and has spread from it far and wide. Innumerable writers, Christian as well as non-Christian, have come to em- ploy the term " Altruism " as a synonym for good- ness. Such assumptions demand our scrutiny. The doctrine has at least two aspects, a psychologi- cal and an ethical. Psychologically, it is assumed that human motives fall into two classes ; one class terminating on the self, and seeking one's own pri- vate good ; the second class terminating upon others, E 49 50 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI and seeking their good. It is further assumed that the division of motives into these two classes is exact and exhaustive. The two classes in question nowhere overlap, and there is no third class of motives. Every action must be done with a view either to our own good or to the good of another, or some others, or all others. A further assumption is noteworthy, both psychologically and ethically. It is assumed that we are able, if we like, to encourage one class of motives and multiply the actions which proceed from it, to discourage the other class of motives, and to weed out or gradually exterminate the actions to which it gives rise. And, finally, there is the ethical as- sumption, that egoistic actions are bad en massey and altruistic actions ethically good, so that plainly we ought to encourage altruism, and do our best to put down egoism. Psychologically, this doctrine involves a notable break with the phenomenalist ethics of the past. Those systems had almost all been established upon psychological hedonism, on the assertion that man necessarily seeks his own pleasure, and cannot possi- bly, in any action, seek for any other end besides his own pleasure. Man, it was conceived, may be mis- informed as to the best means of securing the given end, and therefore there is still room for ethical science as a body of prudential maxims ; it is still possible to say to man, hopelessly and incurably selfish as he is, " you ought " to do this or that ; although upon such a view "you ought" simply means, This will give you the greatest happiness in the long run. Or hedonism might make room for ethics (of a sort) in a different fashion. The moral CHAP, v THE DOCTRINE OF ALTRUISM 51 fellowship of human society might be regarded as a mutual insurance office, in which every one surren- dered small fragments of present happiness in return for a guarantee against great contingent unhappiness in the future. Or by a sort of generous confusion the inference might be urged on men that, as each wants his own happiness, we must all labour for the happiness of all. But the psychological background of these various pieces of special pleading was the assertion that, first and last, each man seeks, and must seek, his own pleasure. The assertion can at times be made to appear almost self-evident, though a few minutes' handling by a skilled cross-examiner l will make it look very foolish indeed. From that psychology to Comte's psychology, from old-fashioned phenomenalism to new-fashioned posi- tivism, is a somewhat startling change. Shall we not welcome it as a change in the right direction ? Cer- tainly a less libellous account of human nature is given when we are told that it is composed of a group of selfish and a group of unselfish motives, than when the old view is reiterated, according to which human nature is root and branch, first and last, by eternal necessity, selfish and only selfish. But we must still inquire whether Comte's amended statement will pass muster scientifically, and, in the first place, psycho- logically. Now, Comte has no belief in a science of psychology. Psychology ought either to fall back upon physiology and phrenology, or to merge itself in sociology. Taken by itself, Comte regards it as a pseudo-science. But the neglected beauty has a capital opportunity for punishing the erring swain 1 Cf. Prof. Sorley's Ethics of Naturalism, pp. 23, 24. 52 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI when Comte begins to talk psychology, for he talks nonsense. One may be confident of support from modern psychology in asserting that every action, however altruistic, is yet in some sense egoistic. It is my action. I should not have made the motive mine, it would not have moved me, unless I had found myself in its results. Mere altruism is mere irrelevance, the action of a lunatic, not of a sane man. Old-fashioned empiricism was right in looking for a personal motive in each action, though gravely in the wrong when it called that personal motive, uniformly and monotonously, by the name of pleasure. But again, with scarcely less confidence, one may assert that even the most egoistic actions are, in a sense, altruistic. Man is so radically social that his sins no less than his virtues are stamped with the signet of his nature. He sins socially. If he does not serve others he uses up others in his own service. Nay, even the cynic is only a social being in a pet. He retains the hope that some one is watching him. Diogenes, basking in his tub, has an exquisite pleas- ure in requesting the great Alexander to stand out of the light. Outwardly withdrawn from society, he is inwardly dependent on it; for admiration, or for criticism, but at any rate for notice. Of course, Comtists may rejoin that they mean to allow for all this. But does their formulation of the case satisfy the demands of science ? Surely Comte, of all men, will not maintain that scientific accuracy is superfluous, or that conduct can be safely guided in the light of slovenly and inaccurate thinking \ A second criticism is offered by Sir J. Fitzjames CHAP.V THE DOCTRINE OF ALTRUISM 53 Stephen in Liberty, E quality > Fraternity}- Justice Stephen, like his brother Mr. Leslie Stephen, is a very severe critic of the weakness of Comte. He protests especially against a further assumption which we noticed in passing, the assumption that it is pos- sible, by careful effort, to readjust the balance of egoism and altruism in human nature. According to Stephen, such a change lies as far beyond our power as a change in gravitation or magnetism, or any of the forces of nature. Sir Fitzjames Stephen does not (here at least) pin his faith to the old selfish psychology of hedonism. Allowing the assumption to pass, that there are a certain number of unselfish promptings in the nature of mankind, or of any given individual, he assumes that (like the elect under the scheme of Calvinism) they can neither be increased nor diminished in number. The criticism, advanced as it is by a determinist, is a very awkward criticism for his fellow-determinists to meet. Speaking as an impenitent freewiller, one admires this pretty quarrel between the forces of the enemy. Stephen appears to be the more logical or consistent determinist, while he is certainly the more impracticable and the more hopeless guide of human conduct. Put in so naked and outrageous a shape, determinism must repel all who love goodness better than they love paradox. Comte's determinism is disguised or kept in the back- ground. He points out that human agency can do absolutely nothing to modify astronomical laws, but that, as we ascend the scale of the sciences, we see physical and chemical forces yielding more and more to human manipulation, until finally, arrived at soci- 1 p. no. 54 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI ology, we may well expect " the human providence " to prove itself nearly omnipotent. Stripped of its Comtist language, all this is true, but it is a truth incompatible with thoroughgoing phenomenalism. Just because man can modify nature, he can more profoundly modify himself. Just because he is not a passive stage, upon which the feelings fight out their battle and settle his destiny for him; just be- cause " man is man, and master of his fate," he puts his mark upon the world in which he lives, and makes it his world. We may now leave the psychological aspects of the doctrine of altruism, and consider its ethical aspects. It has been argued that the sharp contrast between egoistic and altruistic actions or motives is vicious psychology ; and while we have agreed with Comte against Stephen that the forces of human nature are capable of being profoundly modified, we were sceptical as to the possibility of harmonising this fact with the principles of determinism. It re- mains to discuss the ethical significance and trust- worthiness of the altruistic ideal. Its significance in Comte's system is plain enough. It furnishes him with a fresh definition of virtue, as the appeal to biology furnished him with a fresh definition of duty. Less authoritative than the doc- trine of the social organism, the doctrine of altruism appeals to man's moral nature from a different side. To live for self is ala-^pov ; to live for others is /ca\bv /cayaQov. Thus there is a special appeal to motive in this new definition. Perhaps, however, it is best understood as a deliberate rejection of duty to God or to any transcendent standard of worth. Virtue CHAP, v THE DOCTRINE OF ALTRUISM 55 shall be only barely mutual help between man and man. Altruism accordingly is the religion of human- ity itself, considered as a law of conduct between in- dividual and individual. The state is not mentioned ; society is not formally invoked ; but we are bidden live for others. It is easy to see that this doctrine corre- sponds to a part, an element, an aspect of human good- ness. With Comte, however, it stands for the whole. The doctrine finds a response in human nature and the human heart. For, whether recognised or ignored, the moral nature of man is a constant factor in the promulgation and the acceptance of ethical doctrines, healthy or morbid. Conscience is always with us ; it is always more or less active, more or less influential ; and it sees something in " altruism." But, as a formal and exhaustive definition of virtue, altruism claims to stand for everything. And such a claim must be resolutely repelled. If " altruism " were as clearly a psychological fact as it is (we believe) a psycho- logical chimaera, yet, as a contribution to the science of ethics, it must fail.1 Badness is preferring myself to my neighbour; goodness is preferring my neighbour at the sacrifice of myself. Yes, but what is that which it is morally good to bestow upon others ? Surely not the particu- lar sensuous pleasure which I am forbidden to grasp hungrily on my own account ? If a man who drinks wine or beer in moderation gives up his own beer or wine that he may add it to the portion of his neighbour, and allow the latter to indulge a taste for 1 Professor Baldwin (Social and Ethical Interpretations in Mental Development) seems to explode the contrast of egoism and altruism psychologically, and yet to take it for granted in ethics. 56 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI drinking immoderately, that is highly altruistic be- haviour, but it is not virtuous. Indulgence may be as altruistic as any conduct whatever, yet indulgence is as vicious as any conduct whatever. We need not wonder, therefore, if a further step is taken in criticism of such positions as Comte's. Those who have discovered that we may sometimes do wrong in fostering the pleasure of others naturally go on to ask whether it may not be wrong to drop some of our own pleasures, or, at any rate, to drop some of our own rights ? Thus, in place of Comte's one-sided commendation of the service of others, we are asked to accept, as the true ethical ideal, a doctrine of balance between the claims of others and personal claims. This conception — alternating, it is true, with other conceptions — is found as far back as Bishop Butler. Butler has no very clear doctrine of the con- tents of the moral ideal. That was not the question which mainly interested him. When he had said "Obey conscience," he thought he had given the main instruction required of him as a moralist. Still, the other question cannot be suppressed. Reason- able men must ask, " Granted that we are to obey conscience, what is the general line of its commands ? What is the unifying principle of its various utter- ances ? Surely it is incredible that such a principle should be entirely lacking, and scarcely less so that the principle of goodness should be inscrutable to a reverent human inquiry ! " Butler deals with this further question, but he does so informally in a series of not easily reconcilable obiter dicta.1 Sometimes 1 Cf. Dr. T. B. Kilpatrick's Introduction to Butler's Three Sermons on Human Nature. CHAP, v THE DOCTRINE OF ALTRUISM 57 it seems as if benevolence were the master principle of human conduct. In such passages Butler takes his stand, where Comte afterwards rallied, with the prophets of altruism. Sometimes, again, Butler seems to speak as if conscience guided us just where rational self-love would conduct us were it but sufficiently far- seeing. In such words Butler condescends to the cant, not of our century, but of his own, though he does so with manifest uneasiness, and with a bad grace. But, perhaps most frequently, he anticipates Herbert Spencer in pleading for a balance between egoism and altruism. If we must define the principle underlying good conduct, why, we find there are two ultimate principles. At the back of our moral nature there is, if not an irreducible multitude of special com- mands, yet an irreducible dualism — a pair of regnant principles, and the line dividing them must be drawn by a sort of practical tact. Theory is helpless to reach past this "dual control." It is strange to find this doctrine of balance, this glorifying of compromise, renewed by Herbert Spencer — the second great name in the annals of sociology, the inheritor of Comte's problems and Comte's vocab- ulary. He also assumes the psychological legitimacy of the contrast between " Egoism " and " Altruism " ; but altruism does not rank with him as a compend of all the virtues. It is only one half of virtue, though possibly, in the language of children, "the biggest half." Here again, as formerly, we have to ask, Which is the juster development of the view in question ? If we accept altruism as a conception which is psycho- logically valid and ethically important, ought we, like 58 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI Comte, to press it as hard as we can, or rather, like Spencer, to urge that altruism is good only when balanced by a judicious regard to our own egoistic rights? Perhaps the latter view has more of the remnants of wisdom in it. But the truth is, both views are impracticable ; Spencer's no less than Comte's ; a doctrine of balance no less than a doc- trine which ignores self. The double-minded man is, and remains, unstable. It is impossible to serve two masters. A true moral analysis must recognise some- thing higher in the lowliest duty, and in the common- est act of kindness, than private convenience, whether that of ego or alter. " One person I have to make good — myself. My duty to my neighbour is much more nearly expressed by saying that I have to make him happy — if I may." 1 Yes indeed ; but, in making my neighbour happy, I make myself good; or, if I fail to make myself good, I shall not long make my neighbour happy. Both are duties; or rather both are aspects of the good life, in whose unity they are merged. And in both alike there is a reference to something higher, — call it duty ; call it God's will. In faithfulness to one's own moral vocation, social and spiritual — in faithfulness to " my station and its duties," primarily and literally in the kingdom of Great Britain, but, by ultimate analysis, in that better kingdom which cannot be moved, — one is delivered from the extravagances of altruism, and from the imbecilities of compromise, into the very peace of God. Seeing that men are quite sufficiently selfish, Comte's rhetoric in praise of altruism has probably done little 1 R. L. Stevenson, A Christmas Sermon. CHAP, v THE DOCTRINE OF ALTRUISM 59 harm. As rhetoric, it is passable ; as a rough piece of popular pleading, it will serve. But it is wholly lacking in the scientific quality which we were prom- ised. In other words, it is destitute of exactness, or, one might even say, of truth. CHAPTER VI COMTE'S LAWGIVING Its principles — The separation of the temporal and spiritual powers — Political character of Comte's sociology — Details — Summary IT is not possible for us to give a detailed sketch of the Positive Polity. One can only notice in the briefest fashion how the superstructure answers to the foundation laid, or how the threads that have caught our attention are intertwined in the pattern of the finished fabric. We have noted already the following points : the law of the three stages, or the alleged movement from superstition to science; the movement from militarism to industrialism; the separation of the spiritual and the temporal powers ; and the restric- tion placed on the size of states. The third of these may need a word or two of explanation or comment. Under Positivism the separation of the spiritual and temporal powers is very much a separation between men of theory and men of action. By means of such a separation each class is to develop its own especial excellences, and the theories will be disinterested, while the practice will be — what ? it is hard to say, perhaps more perfectly expert. Surely if any proposal deserves Comte's 60 CHAP, vi COMTE'S LAWGIVING 6 1 favourite reproach of " pedantry " this proposal deserves to be so stigmatised. It is a singular example of his fondness for " Catholicism minus Christianity." The director of conscience is to be made supreme in the whole life of Positivism. The only general observation that need be added is upon the name of Polity. Yes, it is indeed a scheme of politics that Comte has given us. There is no contrast left between the organised life of society and its more strictly sociological aspects as a natural growth. May we not say with Mill that the natural tendency of things is simply set aside ? That no serious effort is made to show that the predicted future has its roots in the past ? May we not repeat our previous statement that the predominant partner in the Polity is neither scientific biology nor scientific history, but the wilful will of Auguste Comte ? Some of the details of Comte's scheme may now be run over. The business of government is to be assigned to a triumvirate of bankers, who are to act as dictators, after consultation with the "supreme pontiff," or head of the spiritual power for all mankind. No more is to be heard of popular rights, they are a metaphysical figment. Henceforth men are to speak only of duties. The dictators will accordingly name their own successors. Limitations on the powers of the dictators will nevertheless exist. First, there will be absolutely free criticism, at the risk of religious excommunication, or boycott, at the bidding of the priests. Secondly, the priests will act as a counter- poise; or rather the spiritual power will do so, 62 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI composed of the priests plus the women phis the "proletariate." The clergy are to be intellectual and moral experts, living on salaries — small salaries. As we know already, they are to be debarred from political power and from business activity. The intellectual training of youth is to be entrusted to them, and also medical practice. They are above all things to beware of specialism. It has been remarked that Comte is almost as much opposed to specialist " pedantry " as to metaphysics. The great champion of scientific certainty is becoming more and more jealous of mere knowledge. Utility is to be everywhere kept in view. Priests are to " direct " consciences by counsel, not by force. It will be remembered that they may sometimes advise the dictators, and that, where necessary, they are to oppose them. The tremendous weapon of excommunication is in the priests' hands. Business is to be carried on by captains of industry, directing proletaries. But capitalists who have had the benefit of positivist training in youth, and who walk all their days in the fear and love of the " spir- itual power " are sure to regard their position mainly as a social function, and to seek for no profits be- yond a reasonable salary or "living wage." If nec- essary, strikes and lock-outs may still be resorted to ; but such an emergency can seldom or never arise, under the fostering care of a wise priesthood. Every man is to be regarded as doing social service by his work. No mere " cash nexus " is to hold society to- gether. As with one's professional attendant, so with the tradesman or artizan whom one employs, one is to feel that he has earned a debt of friendship. On CHAP, vi COMTE'S LAWGIVING 63 this point Comte's teaching is surely large-hearted and nobly wise. Positivist education, especially as carried on by mothers, will be moral even more than intellectual. And afterwards, the influence of the priesthood, of public opinion, of the boycott, and of some other in- stitutions of positivist religion, will help altruism to gain the mastery. Religion consists chiefly in prayer, offered morning, noon, and night, and addressed to humanity, especially as represented by one's female relatives — mother, wife, and daughter. If any one is lacking in the second or third of these, or if any one's wife or daugh- ter is inadequate to the rdle of representing humanity, one may substitute other ladies in one's mind. Hu- manity consists of the good alone — the good of the past, the present, and the future — along with those races of the lower animals which, being specially ser- viceable to mankind, are " incorporated in humanity." A calendar of saints' days helps to keep the great names of the past in remembrance. For one's own part, one may look forward to something of a similar " subjective " immortality. Along with humanity, the "great being," the earth may be worshipped as the "great fetish," and space as the "great medium" — together constituting a Positivist Trinity. Paris will be the spiritual capital of humanity. Auguste Comte is the first pontiff of the new and definitive form of religion, — a distinction which is no more than fitting in the case of one who combined in his own person the merits of "Aristotle and St. Paul." — Comte ad- mired Aristotle as heartily as he disliked Plato, and he went far beyond Tubingen itself in styling St 64 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTI Paul " the real founder of Catholicism," i.e. of Chris- tianity. He not only fixed all these matters, he fixed innu- merable others. Every man of business was to retire at the age of sixty-three, spending the remainder of his days in advising his son how to carry on the business. Every labourer was to own the house he lived in. Every house was to contain seven rooms — no more, no less. The labourer's salary was to be 100 francs for a month of twenty-eight days, or an equivalent calculated in piece wages. Every treatise was to contain seven chapters, each divided into three parts, each part subdivided into seven sections. Every poem was to contain thirteen cantos, thirteen being another of Comte's sacred numbers. But, Quousque tandem ? Have we not had enough of this version of scientific sociology? In point of fact, we find ourselves, under Comte's guidance, in a world of caprice. Biology gives him a parable of moral truth, not a law ; history offers suggestions to the philosopher, but does not control his judgment ; the ideal of altruism, of which he is the prophet, is an unproved and unsafe assumption. A brilliant and erratic man, he rode his hobbies hard, and threw the reins upon the neck of his fancy as he approached the details of conduct. If science is definite, meas- ured, certain in its utterances, then Comte, in spite of his aspirations, is no true scientific leader for the human race. PART II SIMPLE EVOLUTIONISM — SPENCER, STEPHEN CHAPTER VII DARWINIAN AND SPENCERIAN CONCEPTIONS OF EVOLUTION DARWIN Evolution came as a surprise — Darwin deals with biology — With species only — Taking " Struggle " from Malthus, he perceives in it (Natural) "Selection" — A true cause, but minute; an immensely slow process — Compare the replies to Malthus — Sexual Selection accelerating — Or Use-Inheritance — But too much Lamarck, mak- ing variation not " casual," but purposeful, would render unneces- sary the " Selective " action of " Nature " — Recent doubts as to use-inheritance THE appeal to biology, so far as it was formulated by Comte in the interests of social science, did not seem to possess any great significance. The im- mense rise in importance that was to accrue to biology from the evolutionary theories of this age was hidden even from the best minds of the preced- ing age. Even Hegel speaks scornfully of the fool- ishness of trying to read the purely ideal evolution, described in his system, as a process in time; but those who feel his influence most strongly to-day have generally accepted the identification. Comte goes further still. He expressly names hypotheses F 65 66 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN K!DD PART n regarding the origin of species among the wasteful and unprofitable inquiries which the human provi- dence will discourage and put down. So unfit are even the learned to play the part of providence. So liable are they to misjudge doctrines which, even if destined at last to be regarded as one-sided and more or less fallacious, have yet shown themselves im- mensely fruitful in suggestions bearing upon every branch of human knowledge. 4 It is now admitted by able adherents of Comte's system l that the doctrine of evolution supplies a background or basis for Comte's unification of knowledge. In such a statement Spen- cer's form of evolutionary doctrine seems to be most directly contemplated, and Spencer is perhaps the least thoroughly biological of all the evolutionary thinkers, whether moralists or sociologists, whom we shall have to pass in review.' Yet the great move- ment of our day was in connection with a biological doctrine which Spencer will certainly not repudiate. And it falls to us rather to argue for a difference than for a kinship between Spencer and Darwin. The kinship is claimed, asserted, conceded.2 We do not deny it; but we believe that the differences reach deep down. Before we go further we must take a hurried view of evolution as conceived by both these influential writers — and first, as conceived by Darwin. Darwin's problem, vast as it was, and bold as was 1 e.g. Mr. J. C. Oliphant in Chambers^ Encyclopaedia, gth edition. 2 Mr. C. W. Williams, of whom Mr. Spencer complains, certainly seems to underrate Spencer's originality (in comparison with Darwin) upon p. 2 of his Evolutional Ethics ; but he makes concessions on the other side upon p. 28. Our desire is to show that the two great men moved on different lines. CHAP, vii EVOLUTION IN DARWIN 6/ the effort required to deal with it, was strictly limited. It lay within the world of .organic life. It sought to account for the origin of distinct species among plants and animals. Organic evolution, as taught by Dar- win, means, one takes it, the evolution of organisms, a doctrine of evolution versus (special) creation as accounting for species, though the phrase organic evo- lution is sometimes perhaps used by other writers1 in a wider, or vaguer, or deeper significance. Darwin himself, as a specialist, had nothing to say to us on the origin of life, nothing, assuredly, on the origin of the universe. At one point, indeed, he unavoid- ably opened up very deep problems. For among the species with which he dealt was the human race ; and a discussion of the origin of mind involves a reference to the beginnings and ends of all things ; it forces us back to first principles and drives us on to the final problems. But of this, perhaps, Darwin was never adequately aware. Every one who has studied philosophy sees it, but Darwin, though a specialist of genius, and a specialist on a great scale, was still, after all, a specialist. And he never claimed to bring the world a new cosmical philosophy ; it was enough for him to introduce one new hypothesis, link- ing together all forms of life, and to see this hypoth- esis conquering mind after mind, until the whole civilised world seemed to bow to its discoverer. Dar- win dealt with the evolution of species, Spencer has dealt with the evolution of the universe. What, again, was the special contribution made by Darwin to his problem — so old a problem, with 1 eg. Dr. E. Caird. In a deeper significance, perhaps, as implying necessary or organic relation between the organism and its environment 68 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n which so many minds had grappled, and, on the whole, so very unsuccessfully ? Primarily of course it was the doctrine of natural selection through the struggle for existence. As students of social phi- losophy, we are specially interested to recall that Malthus's doctrine of population directed Darwin's attention to the aspect of struggle in nature, a fact or aspect of things which he speedily traced through- out all living nature, vegetable or animal. But the doctrine of natural selection — of survival of the fittest l — of improvement of species through the struggle, and gradual development of new species — that was Darwin's own brilliant corollary. He perceived that selection was sure to accompany struggle, if at least there were any differences or variations separating competitors from each other. The best man, or brute, or plant must win, upon the average, and in the long run, if only there were better and worse, better and best, blended in the competition. Other- wise struggle might mean deadlock and mutual ex- haustion, as of two equally matched armies after a long campaign, and general doom to extinction, as of the survivors from a wreck when food runs short. But variations do notoriously exist. Nature, which, "red in tooth and claw," unmistakably asserts the fact of struggle, not less clearly reveals the fact of selection with its two sides of defeat and victory, and with its basis in a tendency to vary. This variation is mainly conceived as congenital. Some are born better, some worse. Not only are the offspring of better parents better equipped ; within the same family, as experience shows, some are better equipped than * Spencer's phrase, however. CHAP, vii EVOLUTION IN DARWIN 69 the rest, some sink below the average. How far this tendency to vary went, Darwin never dogmatically affirmed. It was enough for him usually to treat it as casual and therefore as undefined. The great concern of nature, the arch examiner, was not to secure good candidates, but to secure a plentiful flow. If there were but enough, some good speci- mens would assuredly be found. So said, so done ; teeming nature, as we call it, brought forth all things abundantly, ay, and superabundantly ; not monoto- nously, in mechanical batches, but with minute yet important differences ; the result was continuous ad- justment, and adaptation, and evolution, and improve- ment, at the cost of a heavy and remorseless "pluck," year after year, age after age. Finally, what varia- tion, and struggle, and selection have beaten out, heredity preserves. Within the limits of variation heredity perpetuates, in the offspring, the good and victorious qualities of the parents. This, in very rough and brief outline, is the central portion of Darwin's hypothesis, — the doctrine of natural selection through struggle. When this doc- trine is applied to morals or politics, we have Darwin- ism in morals or politics. Where this doctrine is ab- sent or subordinate, we may have evolutionism in morals or politics ; Darwinism we have not. In this lay Darwin's superiority over many evolutionist prede- cessors, he had laid his finger upon a vera causa, an undeniable fact in nature, — the abundance of off- spring, or — otherwise roughly stated — the scanti- ness of food; upon an undeniable tendency in na- ture ; a tendency to improve and modify all living forms, — improving them, i.e., so far as to make 70 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n them fitter to survive in their given environment. Theories like Lamarck's of the direct action of en- vironment might be plausible, but they seemed to lack verification. Darwin's theory sprang into a dif- ferent position because it appealed undeniably to real facts ; although it gave them a very startling exten- sion in the range of their operation. Certainly the plain man would have said that the tendency, though real, was too infinitesimal for its work. One would have said that natural selection was as utterly unable to explain variety of species, as Sadler's doctrine, or Herbert Spencer's hope, to meet the difficulties alleged by Malthusianism regarding the human race. No doubt, human reproduction becomes less rapid as population thickens. < The alleged self-correcting tendency of the growth of population is a true cause, so far as it goes ; or rather it is a group of causes, urgently requiring to be disentangled, to be studied, named, estimated one by one ; but, in their whole re- sult, they are altogether insufficient to check over- population. And in like manner Spencer's cause is a true cause. It is undoubtedly true that there is a general correlation of fecundity with a low position on the evolutionary scale ; it is true that, as mental and aesthetic interests count for more, the physical tendencies of sex will count for less in the human race ; yet, as far ahead as we can trace, there will still be problems of population. So one would have said of natural selection too : It is a true cause, but cannot possibly do the work asked of it. Its effects are minute; being minute, they will be immensely slow in achieving anything. A blind and indirect method of selection, by striking out all the unfit — CHAP, vn EVOLUTION IN DARWIN 71 by trial and error — is the most tedious method possi- ble. If at every cross-roads I have to follow each track in turn, taking them as they come, going on in each case to the next town before I can learn whether I am on the right road, — if I am wrong, coming back from the town to my cross-roads and trying the next track till I find a town upon it, and so forth and so forth — plainly, it may take me all my days to work my way to my chosen destination. Darwin's theory, however, includes other elements besides natural selection ; and these, if reliable, seem to point to agencies which would accelerate the pro- cess of evolution. One addition which Darwin pro- posed to his doctrine was sexual selection. " None but the brave deserves the fair" — that is half the new doctrine. For sexual selection is believed to ex- ist in two forms: first, when the males fight with each other for the privilege of access to the females, as in the case of lions or stags ; secondly, when the males vie with each other in aesthetic attractiveness, as Darwin supposed to be the case with birds, and as a larger number of observers believe to be demon- strated in the case of certain insects. The assump- tion appears to be that the unsuccessful males remain almost or altogether sterile by force of circum- stances; accordingly, a criticism passed by Wallace upon Darwin's theory of a sexual selection in the case of birds is to the effect that, apparently, even the least beautiful of male birds finds a mate sooner or later during the pairing season ; that the inferior forms leave offspring as well as the superior forms ; that accordingly no selection between different forms is due to the imperfect rivalries of courtship. It 72 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n might be possible, surely, to meet even this difficulty. Presumably, the successful males, whether fighters or beauties, will pair off with the most desirable females; there will be an intensified divergence of offspring in the next generation, with consequent emphasis upon variation, and hastening of the final victory of the strong over the weak. On the other hand it may be held that sexual selection — in this sense — is only a remedy for an obvious weakness in the process of natural selection, — the danger that advantages will be lost by crossing. But if, as is usually thought, sexual competition implies the celi- bacy or nearly so of the unsuccessful candidates ; then we have before us a direct and psychical pro- cess of selection, not an indirect and natural process ; a short and straight process therefore, not a long and circuitous one. Of course, one is not guilty of the absurdity of saying that the females are conscious of a preference for the best male specimens qua best, or are urged by an enthusiasm for the ideal ! We only affirm that, in virtue of their animal minds, they yield themselves to the stronger or to the fairer. Yet again a question may be raised, whether the evolution of beauty, supposed to enter into the second form of sexual selection, is necessarily the same thing as an evolution in strength and efficiency. It may well be so. Beauty may well be correlated to those qualities of health and vigour which make a type intrinsically fitted to survive. As Mr. Grant Allen once remarked in a rare moment of inspiration or common sense, the saying that beauty is only skin-deep is itself but a piece of skin-deep and superficial wisdom. Yet, even if beauty does not imply superior health and vigour, CHAP, vii EVOLUTION IN DARWIN 73 so long as beauty is not developed at the sacrifice of useful qualities, sexual selection will hasten the evolu- tionary process along lines on which it has already begun to move — along the line of beauty, if not in- contestably along the line of strength or aggregate fitness. Another supplement to Darwin's central doctrine is what may conveniently be termed use-inheritance. This played a great part in the evolutionary theories of Lamarck, along with a still more questionable doctrine, that of direct adjustment of the organism to its environment. As the comic song puts it, the giraffe got a long neck by stretching to reach the upper branches. That is scarcely Darwinism ; it is much nearer Lamarckism. The Darwinian giraffe happened to be born with a longer neck than the remainder of his family, and consequently outlived them all in a time of scarcity, and was the only giraffe who transmitted his qualities to offspring. If the giraffe stretched its muscles and its vertebrae to their utmost, and begat a son whose neck, un- stretched, was as tall as the parent's in his habitual tiptoe attitude, that would be use-inheritance — one- half of Lamarck's doctrine, and an accredited though a subordinate portion of Darwin's. If, however, the hungry giraffe organised in itself by some means or other an extra joint, or an extra set of muscles, or, as would probably be necessary, both, that would be a grotesque illustration of the second half of La- marck's theory, — of direct action by environment in the way of modifying an organism ; a grotesque illustration of a sufficiently grotesque belief. At times, it is said, Darwin writes as if he were willing 74 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n to admit this, viz. as a source of variations. But he has never formulated a theory of the cause of varia- tions. He is content, as we observed, to treat them as casual. That, however, cannot mean that they are uncaused, or that the uniformity of nature breaks down as we approach microscopic cell processes. Perhaps at the utmost we can justify the phrase by taking it to mean that congenital variations from the parental qualities are neither on the average advantageous to the species, which might be re- pudiated as a somewhat strong teleological doctrine, nor yet disadvantageous to the species, a view which would imply a sort of dysteleology, as if we lived in the devil's world, and evolution had to go on with a dead heave in spite of the recalcitrance of nature. Chance or accident in common language means " not purposed," and it may perhaps be fair to call varia- tions " casual," if they stand on the average neutral to the purpose or end of the species, viz. to survive and propagate itself. Still the epithet used without analysis is rather slovenly, and any thinking which is fairly summarised by the use of that epithet must be regarded as rather slovenly too. Or, if we hesi- tate to say this of Darwin, we may at least affirm that he left much ground for subsequent investiga- tion. He concerned himself but little with the laws determining variation. There were variations ; there were candidates of varying degrees of merit. Get me candidates, he said in effect; I will give you an examiner who, however tedious in method, is in the long run unerringly wise. Nature will select, come the variations how they may. At times, as we have said, Darwin seems willing to accept Lamarck's CHAP, vii EVOLUTION IN DARWIN 75 cruder and less verified doctrine, of a direct self- adjustment of the organism to the environment as a source of variation. Plainly, however, if this does occur, then, so far as it occurs, it supersedes natural selection. The supplement to the theory will dis- place the theory itself. Those called in to give help as allies will remain as absolute sovereigns. There is no need of indirect methods for compassing a teleological result, if such a result may come about directly through the living powers of the organism. We shall do well then to neglect this admission by Darwin in favour of extreme Lamarckism, par- ticularly as it seems to be a mere obiter dictum)- Even use-inheritance, however, will avail to shorten the process of natural selection. The offspring will start at the point which the parents had reached when it was conceived, not at the point where the parents themselves started, nor yet at that points/us a certain amount of casual variation. On the other hand, we shall have to notice later on that this accelerating process of use-inheritance is much less confidently believed in to-day than in the hour of Darwin's abso- lute supremacy. 1 Darwin's clearest references to the causes of variation are prob- ably found in his Variation of Plants and Animals under Domestica- tion. The theme is therefore a restricted one, and it must be added that the language employed is less clear than would be wished. The following references may be consulted: vol. ii. pp. 290, 305, 311, 552. It should be added that to a certain extent any reliance on Lamarckian factors, even for " use-inheritance," tends to throw the tedious process of natural selection into the background. CHAPTER VIII DARWINIAN AND SPENCERIAN CONCEPTIONS OF EVOLUTION — SPENCER A cosmic philosophy — Resting on correlation of forces — And on hypothesis of organic evolution — Emphasising natural (physical, material) law — Darwinism as a cosmic philosophy ? Alexander — Cf. Lotze — Cf. Fiske — Spencer values true use-inheritance as accounting for a priori knowledge — But natural selection is not the source of his laissez fairc doctrine ; he looks forward to a future " balance " — His relation to embryology — Evolution means grow- ing complexity — In terms of matter — Two other phases — Disso- lution as death — As catastrophe — Equilibrium is theoretical and prophetic — Spencer's sequence of the three phases — Criticisms : on the assumed beginning of the process — On its isolation — On equilibrium, as involving a different point of view — Reason is more than a new phase of complexity — The whole process breaks up into a series of separate evolutions in complexity MR. H. SPENCER'S problem is wider than Darwin's, extending, as it does, to the whole of the phenomenal or " knowable " universe. The impulse to it came from two scientific theories of the age. The first was Grove's proof of the correlation of the physical forces, clenched by Joule's determination of the mechanical equivalent for heat. As a result of this, the inorganic world seemed to gather itself together in one, and to manifest its unity as it had never done before. Phenomenally, the differences remained; heat was heat, light was light, electricity was electricity ; but 76 CHAP, vin EVOLUTION IN SPENCER 77 it was now proved that some were mutually converti- ble, and it was henceforth probable that all were so ; it was known that some were modes of motion, and it came to be believed with increasing definiteness that all the others were equally modes of motion. In the invisible world of molecular change it was as- sumed that these diverse branches combined in one common trunk. The second discovery was Darwin's account of the origin of species. Before this theory was broached Spencer was already on the track of his own thoughts. If it helped him it did so rather by confirming his original bias than by making him a convert to the special peculiarities of Darwinism. In its simplest shape Spencerian evolution is an as- sertion of the all-sufficiency of natural law, a denial of intervention from outside at any stage in the process by which the universe has become what it is. Moreover, natural law means here strictly physical law ; everything is to be explained in terms of " mat- ter and motion." This denial of all miracle, and of everything analogous to miracle, gives evolution its charm in the eyes of a fighting evolutionist like Mr. Edward Clodd. On Spencer's premises " there is nowhere else" outside the process whence interfer- ence might come. Mr. Spencer is confident that he can account for the beginning of the whole process. The inorganic world has been unified by one dis- covery, the organic by another. True, the transition from one to the other had not yet been cleared up in terms of natural law; nor has that been done, one may add, until this day ; but by an act of scientific faith Spencer affirms that the last remaining gap must also be filled up, and natural law remain as the 78 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART u power from which all things have proceeded — master of the whole situation. When we ask whether there is any close connection between Spencer's philosophy and the doctrine of struggle for existence, we feel at once that Darwinism is almost impossible as a cosmic philosophy. Pro- fessor Alexander seems, indeed, to contemplate giving a position of universal importance to the Darwinian doctrine when he writes as follows : " The application of evolution to morals may mean only the employ- ment of biological ideas ; or it may mean that morals must be treated as one part of a comprehensive view of the universe, in which a steady development may be observed from the lowest to the highest phenom- ena, and a development, it may be added, which follows the law of the survival of the fittest'' 1 The use of biological ideas we have seen in Comte, though doubtless only in one of many possible applications. We shall not find much more in Mr. Leslie Stephen's Ethics, though he has of course, in the background, a belief in evolution on the grand scale, as a cosmic philosophy. Spencer works out such a philosophy, and we see in it a considerable amount of pressure directed upon ethics from other parts of the fabric of knowledge. But in Spencer there is no attempt to take the law of the survival of the fittest out of its biological limits, and to give it a cosmic significance* So far as he traces an influence from one cosmic system upon another which has advanced any dis- tance along the evolutionary path, he regards such influence as purely mischievous. It makes for dis- solution, but not for evolution. Perhaps even Mr. 1 Moral Order and Progress, p. 14. CHAP, vin EVOLUTION IN SPENCER 79 Alexander did not seriously mean to include the physical " universe " in his Darwinian scheme. Com- peting organisms we know ; are competing universes anything better than a delirious dream ? Organisms die out, not because they are too ill-balanced for the tasks of life, but because they are, on the whole, in their own environment, inferior to other organisms, and therefore succumb in the competition. We must go back to very early "pioneers of evolution" — to Democritus or Empedocles — if we are to find sur- vival of the fittest seriously applied to the cosmic process. Yet its logical possibility is pressed upon us by so distinguished a man of science, philosopher, and theist as Hermann Lotze. " With reference to the past, we are at liberty to assume that at first an innumerable multitude of inharmonious forms, intrin- sically hostile to any end, actually emerged from the reciprocal impact of blind elements ; that these forms, however, were not able to maintain themselves in the course of nature, as against the contrary assaults from without; that on the contrary only those few held out which had chanced to be the more fortu- nate ; that then these fortunate ones exerted more and more a determining influence upon the rest; and that thus gradually it has come to pass that nature runs its course, not indeed in complete and perfect conformity to an end, but after all to such an extent that there still remain but few disturbances or interferences by which the development and perpetu- ation of the structures that are conformable to an end is endangered. In this way, therefore, it would not be unthinkable that an original chaos gradually shaped itself into a nature that is arranged in con- 8O FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART II formity to ends." 1 Moreover, the postulate under- lying such a view — in Lotze's opinion, of course, a mere logical abstract possibility ; in no wise a fact — is given on the previous page : " If we take for granted that an indefinite multitude of different ele- ments act upon one another entirely in accordance with mechanical laws, and that they were aboriginally in reciprocal motions, which were not regulated by any design." This postulate, named by Lotze only that he may presently dismiss it as metaphysically untenable,2 is identical, not perhaps with Spencer's, but certainly with his disciple Fiske's, " the mere co- existence of innumerable discrete bodies in the uni- verse, exerting attractive and repulsive forces upon each other."3 Spencer, perhaps characteristically, prefers to give us vague glimpses of a "homogeneous " though highly "unstable " continuum in space, finite in its dimensions, as the origin of all change. We con- clude, therefore : a cosmic philosophy might perhaps be grounded on a more than Darwinian apotheosis of competition. But no modern has tried to work out such a scheme — unless Lotze in one of his paradoxi- cal moods as the candid friend of theism. Fiske might have been tempted in that direction, but was not. Spencer did not even cast one glance towards it. "Only one part of Darwin's theories is specially important to Spencer — the Lamarckian doctrine of use-inheritance. That is the basis of Spencer's reconciliation of Intuitionalism with Empiricism. We 1 Outlines of Philosophy of Religion, tr. p. 20. 2 The many elements reducing themselves to elements in one great system ; the separate processes to one many-sided evolution. 9 Cosmic Philosophy, ii. p. 867. CHAP, viii EVOLUTION IN SPENCER 8 1 modern men' possess intuitive knowledge — partly of mathematical, partly of moral truth — simply because our ancestors have had a wide range of experience of mathematical and moral facts, and have been able to impart their principles to us in the shape of innate tendencies to believe — tendencies which forestall experience and anticipate its results ; generally with accuracy. Thus Spencer has an answer for many difficulties. What gives conscience its awful author- ity over the human spirit ? What makes right and wrong so different, psychologically, from a calcula- tion of consequences ? Why, the experience of law- abiding and dutiful generations, whose blood flows in your veins. Again one asks, what is the hold that the public weal has upon me, a separate individual, with my own desires, ay, and my own rights? But his reply is ready. The tribal or national con- science is within you ; it is a part of you from your birth ; sinning against it you sin against what is best in yourself. Morally, however, Spencer gives this no great range, and his colleague or disciple, Mr. Leslie Stephen, writes a treatise on ethics without once mentioning it. Spencer is little inclined to admit true moral axioms ; he is resolved to keep the door open for a phenomenalist doctrine of " causal connexions " in conduct, if not exactly for hedonistic sophistications. It is elsewhere that he has frankly confessed the existence of axioms, mathematical or " transcendental." He has got his explanation of these, if he is allowed the appeal to use-inheritance ; but if not ! Spencer is fighting for his hearth and home and for all that he counts most sacred, when he girds himself to refute Weismannism off the face 82 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n of the earth. Apart from use-inheritance, indeed, one does not see how the evolution of mind is ever to be made decently intelligible, unless because " intelli- gence " was in the beginning a " casual variation " of small amount — and the stupider specimens died out, etc., etc! That explanation will never fail those whom it can satisfy. *• Except on this point of use-inheritance, Spencer is hardly to be regarded as Darwinian in his thinking. Natural selection has hardly influenced his statement. I do not mean that he refuses help from the doctrine, when he finds help offered incidentally, in the bio- logical or historical region. He is too good a tacti- cian to do that. But Professor D. G. Ritchie seems quite unwarranted in explaining Spencer's laissez faire individualism by his bigoted attachment to the doctrine of natural selection by struggle. Far from that ; Spencer's golden age of individualism lies in the future, in a period of equilibrium ; but if struggle is all-important, such a period can never arise. Over against Darwin's conception of many organisms competing with each other, Spencer sets up a pic- ture of one great peaceful process. Mr. Leslie Stephen tells us we ought perhaps to regard human- ity as a single organism ; Spencer seems almost to regard the whole of the universe as one great organic growth. Embryology shows him the simple, almost homogeneous cell differentiating itself and growing complex ; it is the same process Spencer traces in the universe, though he states it in terms barely of " matter and motion." * 1 Spencer has admitted his indebtedness to von Baer, the embry- ologist, for the idea to which he has given so wide an extension. CHAP, vin EVOLUTION IN SPENCER 83 What then is evolution, that key to the whole knowable universe, as stated in Spencer's own sys- tem ? What are its great laws, or what are the prop- erties manifested by " matter and motion " as the subjects of evolutionary change ? There is one word which may state sufficiently for our purposes what is meant in Spencer by evolution — the word complexity. Evolution means growing com- plexity ; more complex is more evolved. Whatever technicalities are unfolded in the successive definitions given in the course of the volume upon First Prin- ciples, they do not carry us beyond this contrast of the simple and the complex. They are drawn up " in terms of matter and motion," which means that the details of the definitions apply to inorganic matter or to the physical basis of life, but cease to bear any meaning in psychology and sociology, in what Mr. Spencer calls " superorganic " evolu- tion. It may plausibly be held that, as knowledge advances, thought grows continually more complex, though it may be questioned with something more than plausibility whether it is possible in ultimate analysis to resolve the complex of consciousness into isolated presentations — even if we throw them into the region of the subconscious. Complex grows more complex as knowledge advances, but complex is complex, not simple, in the very first manifestation of knowledge. Evolution, then, may be applied to mind as well as to matter in the sense of growing com- plexity; but what shall we make of the statement that there is an integration of matter and concomitant dissipation of motion, during which the matter passes from an indefinite incoherent homogeneity to a definite 84 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART 11 coherent heterogeneity, and during which the retained motion undergoes a parallel transformation ? Thought cannot be stated in terms of matter and motion; there is a gulf between the two. No doubt brain may grow more and more complex as mind advances ; but that is a physiological truth, not a psychological ; and Spencer vindicates psychology against Comte's criticisms as a separate science. Well, then, even if this science exemplifies the evolutionary tendency to complexity, it does not, and cannot, fulfil Spencer's formulated law of evolution. The case is no less clear as regards sociology or ethics. But what is the use of a law that does not fit the facts ? What is the use of claiming to give an interpretation "in terms of matter and motion "when the terms them- selves rebel against the office to which they are put ? Evolution, however, is not the only great interpre- tative category which Mr. Spencer has in view. It is flanked by two others — dissolution and equili- bration. Dissolution is the opposite of evolution. Equilibration stands between the two — the last stage in evolutionary process within any finite aggregate before the forces of dissolution break in from the out- side. At first sight nothing can seem more trivial or truistic than this threefold view of nature. Every- where things are either growing more complex, or else getting less complex, or else standing still with- out either gain or loss. No doubt, but pray what else could things do ? Did it need a great philoso- pher, controlling all the thought of the past and all the science of the present ; did it need a system of philosophy in a dozen volumes to teach us this pedantic formula ? CHAP, viii EVOLUTION — SPENCER 8 5 Yet perhaps there is rather more underneath the surface, whether well founded or ill. First, as to dissolution. Dissolution is by no means of equal importance, in Spencer's systema- tising of knowledge, with evolution. At times, theoretically, he may co-ordinate the two ; but nine- tenths of his energy is spent in showing how nature weaves her web ; barely one-tenth is allotted to the process of unpicking the fabric and resolving it again into its threads. In one form dissolution has a place in the system of nature as we know it, viz. in the law of death, which is so general in the organic world. But surely it needs no argument to prove that dis- solution, taken in this sense, does not counterbalance evolution, or even neutralise it pro tanto. Death is an element in the evolving system of organic life. Darwin has taught us to regard death as the great implement by which progress is secured through the weeding out of the less fit and vigorous forms. Weismann has conjectured that the habit of dying a natural death, however originated, may have been a direct advantage to the mortal species, clothed as a species with perpetual youth, in contrast with rudi- mentary or hypothetical species of living creatures which were potentially immortal.1 But, apart from such questions, we know that death is accompanied by reproduction, and is balanced by it, and that the great evolutionary differentiation of plants and animals from the one-celled type has gone on in the midst of death. Surely, then, dissolution is a mere incident or episode 1 Weismann does not admit that he thinks of a literal struggle be- tween essentially mortal and potentially immortal forms. What then does he mean, — he, a hyper-Darwinian? 86 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n in evolution so far as we are to identify dissolution with death. There is, however, a further sense in which dissolu- tion may be regarded as the opposite of evolution — if it come as a great cosmic catastrophe, bringing to an end (e.g.) the adjustment which has kept the solar system in equilibrium during untold ages. Of course such a crash on such a scale must tell not merely upon planetary evolution, but upon any organic or superorganic evolution, of which the planets in ques- tion had been the scene. From this point of view any disastrous tempest, or earthquake, or volcanic eruption may be regarded as a sample of dissolution. The larger occurrence of similar forms of dissolution Mr. Spencer seems to keep in reserve in order to account for the end of all things phenomenal. Considering the various applications of the term, may we not say that dissolution differs from evolution, not merely in tendency or direction, but also in rate of speed ? That the one is slow and gradual, the other abrupt and cataclysmic ? This is a fresh reason for declin- ing to admit that the two terms are of equal impor- tance in Mr. Spencer's thinking. Passing next to speak of balance or equilibrium, we notice that, in Mr. Spencer's system, balance is not mainly contemplated as a phenomenon of experience, occurring in a relative sense, or up to a limited ex- tent, and accompanying the processes of evolution. Mr. Spencer, of course, is fully aware that life, e.g., is a " moving equilibrium." But beyond that truth of experience there presses on his mind a supposed truth of theory, a doctrine of equilibrium, in which balance is strongly contrasted with evolutionary pro- CHAP, vin EVOLUTION — SPENCER 8/ cess as the limit of evolution, and the goal to which it tends. Accordingly Mr. Spencer gives us this curious pic- ture of the eternal and necessary nature of things : every system of matter and motion, which admits of being studied by itself, and which is subject to no in- fluences from without except such minute ones as may fairly be disregarded, — if it is in a state of com- parative simplicity, must, by eternal necessity, grow more and more complex, till at length it has perfectly worked out the inner scheme of possibility prescribed to it by its original deposit of matter and motion. When it has done this evolution must cease, equilib- rium superseding it. In this sense of the term equi- librium now begins to reign. And the reign now begun, so far as appears, might, for good or for evil, be eternal, so perfect will the inner equilibrium have become, — if only there were not other systems of matter outside the balanced system of which we are speaking — other systems which, sooner or later, will interfere in its affairs with a crash of dissolution. Then comes the third and shortest act in this drama. Hitherto subordinate, counterbalanced, overruled, dis- solution will now be master of all ; the web of changes, so slowly woven, so long preserved, will be rapidly torn into shreds ; the wheel will have come full cir- cle, and nature will begin once again "at the very beginning." By this time the evolutionary doctrine of Mr. Spencer has ceased to bear any resemblance to a truism. Vague as are its terms, they are sufficiently startling. Fichte seemed a bold man when he an- nounced a test for all possible revelations ; Spencer is 88 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART il not less bold when he prints a programme for all pos- sible universes! And all this is in the name of science — the old and sober science of mathematics. Spencer assumes a definitely limited stock of matter, a definitely limited stock of force, or, as he prefers to say, of motion ; and he alleges that every universe, constituted of these materials, must continuously be- come more and more complex, until it reaches a bal- ance and ultimately is wrecked by an impulse from without. If this is a scientific certainty, so be it. Yet, without attempting to control Mr. Spencer's use of science, one may express surprise at two or three features in the scheme. First, there is the perplex- ing doctrine of the instability of the homogeneous. It would have been so much simpler for nature to remain what it was than to work out a position of balance by more than aeonian evolution, only to re- turn once again to homogeneity and instability. So far, the doctrine seems to be this : evolution is neces- sarily originated because of the very nature of matter and force. Secondly, one may express surprise that the forces from without should be assumed to act only at the very beginning of all things, or at the very end of all things. If they can tear up a worn-out uni- verse, are they not likely to tear up the majority of universes before they have so much as half run their course ? Their interference may be orderly enough ; it may only result in a richer capitalising of the busi- ness ; but assuredly if such things happen, evolution will need to start de novo. Thirdly, the grounds for the theory of equilibrium are not manifest to the plain reader. If matter and force can and must initi- ate a process of growing complexity, and push it on CHAP, vni EVOLUTION — SPENCER 89 for ages, are we sure there is a reason in the nature of things compelling this oscillation to cease ? Does not the doctrine of final balance point to a different conception of evolution, as if it depended, not on the healthy nature of matter and force, but on a certain disturbing element, and as if, when the disturbance was once adjusted, progress ceased ? So long as the stoppage is supposed to affect only one limited evolv- ing system, interference may come from other limited systems outside, and renewed evolution may take place. But we must not always study nature piece- meal. And, if the whole of nature works into a final balance, which, as Mr. Spencer says, may very well turn out to be a thing kindred to death rather than to life, then the whole of nature will remain there as still as a stone — the clock having run down, will continue at rest till the end of eternity. There is, however, another point still to notice in characterising Spencer's views of evolution. He not only asserts evolution, as the good and grand side of nature, in aeons of necessary and continuous growth in complexity; he assumes under evolution things much more wonderful than any complexity — he as- sumes life and thought. As far as his formula goes, the universe might run its course and reach the end of its tether without ever quitting the region of the inorganic. That is the result of stating evolution " in terms of matter and motion " ; your definition does not apply to the higher manifestations of nature. Our universe, however — or let us say our world — has reached such higher manifestations. It has trav- elled all the way from the assumed solar nebula, not merely to planets, not merely to rocks, and water, and 90 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n atmosphere, but to plants, and brutes, and men, and societies, and ethical systems, and schools of philoso- phy. All these are accordingly claimed and tabu- lated among the workings of evolution. But the formula does not point to them. It must therefore be improved in some way. We may turn here to theism, using it as of old in supplement to the for- mulas of science. God works on nature from out- side. Evolution causes nothing. It may be God's method. He causes all these great results. Or else the formula must be amended, and we must interpret the process by its highest stages, not by its lowest — by life and thought rather than by matter and force. This issue must really be fairly faced. Either life and thought are an anomalous by-product (whatever that may mean) in the story of a universe which is purely and essentially material ; or life and thought are the interpretation of nature — the end for which it exists — the hinted justification of its age-long travail and agony. The two opposing views come out very clearly in Mr. Fiske's version of Spencer's positions, and one is glad to know that, of later years, in Mr. Fiske's case, the higher and nobler view has gained much ground at the expense of the other. To merge these new orders of existence under the vague heading of "growing complexity" — to assimilate them to purely mechanical redistributions — is not fair-play. The result is this: in his general philo- sophical appeal, Spencer assumes that all existence /reveals a gradual ascent upwards — upwards, i.e., to life and thought.*^ And the knowledge that life and thought have emerged on this earth inclines men to regard favourably the claim of evolutionism to serve UNIVER CHAP, viii EVOLUTION — SPENf as a philosophy. But, when he comes to state his system in detail, the very attempt to trace unity of process is abandoned. Instead of that, we have a number of parallel developments ; material simplicity (homogeneous matter) passing into material complex- ity (universes) ; biological simplicity (the cell) passing into biological complexity (the multicellular organism); psychological simplicity (the presentation or impres- sion or psychical " shock ") passing into psychological complexity (mind); sociological simplicity (the tribe of kinsfolk) passing into sociological complexity (through militarism to industrialism, the final non- coercive order). »' From the formula of " growing complexity " no one could have deduced, or can de- duce, organisation, consciousness, history. "-'Again, take Mr. Spencer's subdivisions in any one of the higher sciences. It is well to review the historical phenomena of human society under the heads of domestic, political, ceremonial, and ecclesiastical in- stitutions. These headings are drawn from know- ledge of the special facts to be dealt with. Can any one say that the abstract formula of growing com- plexity suggests these subdivisions ? Is any light thrown upon them by speaking of " aggregations of matter" or "parallel redistributions of contained motion " ? The great German idealistic philosophies may claim our faith, or they may find us no better than doubting Thomases, but at least we owe them this admission, — they have tried to exhibit the world we know as the necessary realisation of one great principle in stage after stage. Mr. Spencer has not been bold enough or rash enough to at- tempt this. But, without doing it, he claims all 92 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART il the advantage of having done it, and of having crowned his efforts with success. If we are able to distinguish words from things, we shall refuse to admit that so great a distinction can be so cheaply earned. CHAPTER IX MR. SPENCER'S THREE DOCTRINES OF HUMAN WELFARE Goodness is more evolved conduct, i.e. is " wisdom " — An appeal to (cosmic) history ! — It is balance, of egoism and altruism — An appeal to economics and to (hedonistic) psychology — It is individ- ual freedom — An appeal to rights, and to (human) history, emerg- ing from militarism — For which Spencer feels an exaggerated dread — Spencer masses facts rather than unifies knowledge — The " so- cial organism " is only a phrase with him HAVING sought to differentiate Spencer's position as an evolutionist from Darwin's, we may now return to our more proper theme, by asking what doctrine or doctrines of human welfare Mr. Spencer furnishes. "' We note three main positions, independent of each other. First, human conduct is good or wise in pro- portion as it is more evolved; secondly, in propor- tion as it draws near the ideal goal of ethical progress, the perfect balance between egoistic and altruistic impulses ; thirdly, in proportion as it is faithful to the high attainments of modern social advance with its ideal of a still higher future, when the compulsory co-operation distinctive of militarism shall have en- tirely given place to the free co-operation distinctive of industrialism. The first of these positions is not specially formu- lated or emphasised by Spencer, but represents an assumption that runs through much of his system, 93 94 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n and that works to the surface at many isolated points. Good conduct is more evolved than bad conduct, and, being more evolved, it is more complex. The bad man is like a clumsy juggler who can barely keep in motion two balls at once ; the good man is like a clever juggler who, without sign of effort, can con- trol his half-dozen balls or more. With this is associ- ated the conception of evil and in particular of crime, as atavism. The criminal is a survival or revival of a lower social type ; he cannot bear the stress of civilisation at its present pitch, and so falls back upon "good old rules" and "simple plans. }> A further implication is plain. So far as this mode of conceiving things is true, moral progress runs par- allel with intellectual progress, and rests upon it. The criminal breaks down because he is psychologi- cally incompetent. Goodness is wisdom. Perhaps such a position is a wholesome corrective of dangers that beset ordinary ethical thinking. When we have begun by distinguishing between intellectual and moral advance and by insisting that one may be found in separation from the other, we are too apt to let the distinction harden into an absolute contrast. It is well to have our attention recalled from sim- plicity, as a moral ideal, to the rival claims of wis- dom. For ultimately all ideals must converge ; and no sort of goodness can long commend itself which fails to make room for the higher tasks of culture and the finer growths of intellect. If we ask next what is the authority for this view of things as as- sumed by Spencer ?< If Comte may be regarded as appealing to biology, to history, and to a half-psycho- logical, half-ethical doctrine of altruism, to what does CHAP, ix MR. SPENCER'S THREE DOCTRINES 95 Spencer here appeal ? We must answer that he ap- peals to the whole cosmic process. It is a kind of appeal to history, but to history generalised and ex- panded far beyond the range of the human race. From the unstable homogeneity of the hypothetical nebulous cloud, beyond which thought can discover no deeper foundations in the abyss of the past, thence on to the present, all things, as they have evolved, have grown ever more and more complex ; let us too join the onward march ; let our minds expand and ramify and interweave their forces ; let us grow ever better and better by growing ever more and more elaborate and intricate in our behaviour ! An im- pressive appeal, if you have any sort of religious faith, theistic or even pantheistic. If " all things are working together for good," then the behaviour of " all things " may well furnish a type for our own conduct. But, apart from the assumptions of reli- gious faith, it hardly seems possible that so abstract a formula as "growing complexity " should command the reverence of the human conscience. And one is driven to ask whether conscience has not its own tests ? And whether Spencer's appeal does not carry its own limited cogency just upon this account, because it has been examined, and, in a sense, coun- tersigned by conscience? Whatever may be the philosophy of conscience, the voice of conscience does not wait for authority from evolutionary doc- trine or from any other outside critic, before telling us, and that in no faltering tones, that goodness is wise, that sin is foolish, and that wisdom, which is one name for goodness, demands from us progress, both intellectual and moral. 96 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n - The second of Spencer's ruling moral conceptions is that of a balance between egoism and altruism. This balance is twofold ; there is to be a balance be- tween egoistic and altruistic promptings in the indi- vidual; and there is to be a balance between personal gratification and social service in experience. But the two processes are to be developed harmoniously, and are to achieve their tasks together. On one side, this draws from Spencer's general evolutionary phi- losophy. It corresponds to that doctrine of final balance which is so dubious and so characteristic an element in his deductive processes. Historically, it probably owes its suggestion to the doctrine of the stationary state formulated by the Political Econo- mists. To them progress meant largely numerical growth in population. When that tremendous press- ure should have to cease for lack of further space, they looked forward to a stationary state of society ; and J. S. Mill at least plucked up courage to regard the stationary state as a thing to be desired rather than dreaded. In Spencer's system, this conception is given the lordship over ethical thought, strictly so- called; and complexity, or the progressive ideal, is overborne by the ideal of balance, or fixity, as a Utopian or millennial vision. Has this ideal any further authority beyond the place allotted to equi- librium in Spencer's First Principles? Assuredly it has. It represents the hedonistic postulate. It represents an appeal to consciousness, and to that form of consciousness which declares pleasure to be the end of life. Distracted between the craving for personal pleasure and the momentous claims of others, the individual is bidden take comfort from the evolu- CHAP, ix MR. SPENCER'S THREE DOCTRINES 97 tionary process, which, moderating personal claims, and increasing altruistic efforts, is preparing a heaven upon earth for the benefit of our very remote poster- ity ; at least, if the world lasts long enough. But the fundamental postulate remains: pleasure is the good. : All systems, we are told, virtually involve this as- sumption, and all moral truths are lighted up by it. Why is altruism good ? Because it gives pleasure to other persons, although at personal cost. Why is egoism good? Because a judicious tincture of egoism increases average happiness. Thus, in this depart- ment of the system, the supreme law is not " Be complex," but " Get pleasure," or, in its noblest form, " Give pleasure," but in the form which best repro- duces the meaning of the doctrine of balance, " Pro- mote maximum pleasure." This psychological test of the good overrides and controls all the other tests with which it is associated in the Data of Ethics — physical, biological, sociological. Spencer himself bears witness to this fact — to the supremacy in his thinking of a psychological test ; nor have any reason to challenge or complain of it. By all means let the moral consciousness speak ; and let it be a supreme, if not a solitary, guide ; but are we sure that this hedonistic doctrine is the authentic and final utter- ance of the moral consciousness? "Is complexity — which in Spencer's thinking stands for moral and in- tellectual progress — really to yield its place of supremacy to compromise or balance, if the latter secures maximum pleasure all round ? The third ideal dominates Spencer's formulated sociological doctrine. Here he is the out-and-out champion of individualism. His sociological law- 98 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n giving distils down into a single old phrase, laissez faire. Of course so acute and systematic a thinker betrays the same bias in his ethical writings as in his sociology. He is a thorough individualist in his emphasis upon justice, with its indefinite appendixes in favour of negative and positive beneficence. Both as moralist and as sociologist, Spencer is full of the thought of individual rights : in curious contrast with previous utilitarian writers, and in curious sympathy with intuitionalism. This doctrine of rights consti- tutes, in fact, one of the most genuine and most important among the vanishing traces of intuitional- ism in Spencer's thinking. Still it seems fair to say that when he handles ethics technically this doctrine of rights is overruled and held in check by a doctrine of maximum pleasure. The Utopian state is not praised on account of its freedom, so much as on account of its balance and harmony. All this is altered when we pass to the technically sociological discussion. Here freedom is the good ; not harmony or co-operation per se, but that harmony or co-opera- tion which results from freedom in contrast with that which results from compulsion. This (sociological) doctrine is supported by an appeal to history. The cosmic philosophy is silent here, except in so far as it hints that the voluntary co-operation of industrialism, being later in origin than militarism, is presumably higher — more truly evolved — more complex. There is hardly any trace of hedonism in the argument. If the appeal to history ran into the form, " Freedom has worked better ; " " Freedom has increased aver- age happiness ; " that would, of course, be sound hedonistic doctrine. But Spencer, like Comte, has CHAP, ix MR. SPENCER'S THREE DOCTRINES 99 little taste for detailed historical parallels as a means of appeal to history; both prefer to look to the mighty onward current, — while unfortunately their witnesses, reporting what they see there, agree not together. Comte regards individual freedom as a sign of the weakness inherent in " critical periods," which can be nothing better than narrow bridges leading from one organic period to another ; Spencer regards individual freedom as the highest stage in evolution — the great good towards which past condi- tions have steadily moved on. Comte, in the name of fact and science, preaches a new synthesis; Spen- cer, speaking in the name of the same great authori- ties, pronounces a curse upon it. Every attempt at closer social organisation seems to him a relapse into outgrown military forms of society, and an act of treason towards industrialism. He does not discuss this, but takes the assumption for granted, with an a priori vehemence that we should find it hard to match, outside the ranks of scientific empiricists. Of course he has informed himself, as few men have done, of the vast prevalence of militarism during former ages. Where society has been highly central- ised or organised, it has been in the past, one might almost say, uniformly, a society of a military type. And a very little study of sociology will make it plain that, if a society is drilled and regimented and over- governed, it will lend itself much more readily to manipulation for military ends than a freer or more individualist society would do. ' Still, all this hardly constitutes a proof. It may be unfair to style it a prejudice : let us call it a presumption, and a grave presumption ; but is it a proof ? The Hindu who TOO FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n mocked at the very idea of ice had a wide experience of the fluidity of water ; and it is perfectly true that H2O tends strongly to the liquid state, being a liquid " at ordinary temperatures and pressures " ; yet solid water is a fact of some importance to Arctic and Atlantic voyagers, whom it brings into danger ; not to mention British outdoor labourers whom the frost robs of work, or plumbers to whom it is better than a mine of gold. Ice then is a fact, though to some it may be a novel fact. And socialism might be a practicable policy even though it be a new development of strict social organisation. It is not disproved by calling it bad names. Neither socialism itself, nor the modern political changes stigmatised by their opponents as socialistic, are in the least degree animated by any conscious breath of the military spirit. They do not mean to serve it ; and, whether they turn out good or evil, we cannot be sure that they will turn out to be in the line of militarism. There is no promise or potency of a coup d'ttat in the Government purchase of telegraphs or even of rail- ways. When Mr. Spencer insists upon treating every civil servant as a disguised soldier and secret con- spirator, he does not carry our convictions with him ; he only proves to us that the new science is very like the old obscurantism, and that you may find a perfect sample of the High Priori temper in a mind wedded to familiar facts, and inaccessible to unfamiliar ones. * Mr. Spencer then has given us three ideals ; and they hardly seem to agree with each other. One is an ideal of progress, two of fixity ; one praises com- plexity, another tells us that the best government is the minimum of government, but that means simplic- CHAP, ix MR. SPENCER'S THREE DOCTRINES IOI ity, not complexity. It is the nature of reason to invent short-cuts and to retrench needless labour. The most advanced is not necessarily the most elabo- rately organised ; it is not so, if Mr. Spencer is right, in society. Moreover, the sources of authority are different. One appeals to the cosmic process; one to the experience and tendency of human history; and one direct to consciousness. In Martineau's lan- guage, Spencer's ethics, technically so-called, are "psychological ethics" though "heteropsychological." Surely we have reason to fear that the promised uni- fication of knowledge is still sadly to seek. Vast masses of knowledge have been collected. They fairly bristle with suggestions — highly interesting, extremely divergent suggestions ; but neither within the four corners of Mr. Spencer's own system, nor when we bring his teaching into comparison with that of other votaries of fact, do we find science still- ing the metaphysical strife, or giving clear guidance in human things. One part of Mr. Spencer's teaching, held by him like some others in common with Comte, has not yet been referred to ;^ his doctrine of the analogy between society and an animal organism. 7I have omitted this, because I regard ifCas an ornamental excrescence on Spencer's teaching, not as an essential or even a sig- nificant part. Whatever function the appeal to biol- ogy played in Comte, it seems to play very little part in Spencer. "The social organism" is an outplayed authority — a god emeritus — a depotentiated deity — on Mr. Spencer's pages. " The social organism " is a metaphor with him and only a metaphor. The indi- vidual cells are asserting themselves, and the unity of IO2 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n the organism is coming off second best. If Comte tells us, " Be parts ; be mere parts, living for the sake of the whole," Spencer thinks such advice the very worst possible. Each for himself ; fair-play all round ; justice the supreme consideration, politically and so- cially ; the occasional surrender of individual rights purely a personal matter, with which public action and public opinion dare not interfere — such is Mr. Spencer's social programme. It is the antithesis of Comte's. Where Comte says, " Yes," Spencer says "No," very nearly all the way through. We take it, therefore, that, beyond serving to explain his views lucidly and add a grace to them, the doctrine of the social organism does nothing for Mr. Spencer, CHAPTER X MR. LESLIE STEPHEN'S "SCIENCE OF ETHICS" Stephen a utilitarian — Who came to believe in evolution as a scientific fact — Begins here with facts ; ethical judgments exist — Organisms seek maximum efficiency — If social " tissue " is " organic " — Then ethical laws may be the conditions of maximum social efficiency — (Nature cares for individuals) — Nature says, " Be strong ! " — Ethics says, " Society, be strong ! " — The ethical is the typical society, and therefore ethical judgments are binding — But the type is actual, not ideal ! — Society is a complex whole, changing while its parts are un- changed — Criticism — Sanction for individual goodness lies in sym- pathy merely — Sometimes we are too good for our own interests ! Compared with Comte, lacks authority — With Spencer, calls " health " the ideal, and ridicules " balance " — With Darwin, not struggle of individual with individual, but of individual with society — With Utilitarianism; discourages the calculation of consequences — Most of his positions may be accepted in a deeper sense MR. STEPHEN makes his intellectual history very plain in the preface to the Science of Ethics. He started in the life of thought as a utilitarian, under the strong influence of J. S. Mill ; and he never came to regard the utilitarian position as discredited. But, in course of time, impressed partly by Darwin's theory, partly by Spencer's writings, he began to crave a re- statement of ethics. This was in no sense a conces- sion to intuitionalism. Spencer's "reconciliation of intuitionalism with empiricism " is indeed accepted by Mr. Stephen, as appears from his other writings ; but, 103 104 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n unless one has read the Science of Ethics very care- lessly, no reference is made to the doctrine in Stephen's moral system, and it seems to go for little with him. Indeed, his first view of evolutionism hailed it as a new stick for beating the intuitionalist dog withal — a new reason for rejecting the conception of ready-made and all authoritative ideas in the human mind. And when he conceived the possibility and desirableness of a new system of morals, he had not in view a worthier ethic than utilitarianism, but rather one more fully in har- mony with new scientific truths. Science, not philos- ophy, demanded the change. Evolutionism must be given effect to. If the change results in a more adequate statement of moral ideas, that is, for Mr. Stephen, a secondary matter. The great thing with him, as on a broader canvas with Mr. Spencer, is to unify thought. One fresh province is to be gained for the master principle, evolution. As Prussia Prus- sianises its Polish dominions, as Russia desires to Russianise Finland, so Mr. Stephen evolutionises his ethics. Of course in each case the conquered is as- sured that ultimately his own interests will be served through accepting the rfgime dictated by the con- queror. When dealing with Comte, we suggested a difficulty for thorough-going phenomenalism in the very con- ception of duty ; and we argued that Comte uses the doctrine of the social organism as justifying the claim for individual submission to the" public weal. Mr. Stephen also makes an appeal to biology, but he does not directly employ that appeal as a basis of ethics. He begins more simply, by accepting current moral judgments. Science deals with facts ; well! these are CHAP, x "SCIENCE OF ETHICS" 1 05 facts. Ideal ethics, indeed, are no facts of everyday experience ; but Mr. Stephen tells us that he has noth- ing — so he says ; nothing — to do with ideal ethics. It is the current rules, which have been historically recognised and appealed to, for which he desires to find a scientific basis. Mainly he is concerned with defining ethics — with reaching greater accuracy than is possible for the colloquial judgments of mankind. His voyage is one of survey and measurement. Ulti- mately his reasonings must bear on the question of the justification of ethical judgments ; primarily, he is concerned with their precise statement. And, indeed, precision is one great mark of science, along with exhaustiveness and coherence. What, then, has evolutionism done for him ? First, it has taught him that every organism strives to attain to its maximum efficiency. Darwin, indeed, has pointed out that the organism which fails to strive, or fails to attain, fails also to survive. There is, how- ever, little direct Darwinism in the Science of Ethics;1 and in its absence Mr. Stephen's view of an organism sounds almost Lamarckian — dreadful word ! — or even — more dreadful still — Spinozistic. He has borrowed from science the fact that each organism seeks maximum efficiency. Darwin's view of the reason of that fact he accepts rejoicingly; but he does not utilise it. Secondly : he agrees with many predecessors in holding that society is essentially organic ; and he gives the usual and correct interpretation of that statement, viz. that in society, as in plants or ani- 1 Some passages on pp. 72, 73, 91, 92, where Mr. Stephen does Darwinise, are quoted in Williams's Evolutional Ethics, 419, 420. 106 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n mals, the whole explains the parts or is prior to the parts ; that you cannot explain the whole as a me- chanical combination of separate parts, but on the contrary, must have a knowledge of the whole before you can correctly define or explain any one part.1 Since man is essentially dependent on society — since man is by nature social — therefore we call society an organism. It is doubtful whether we can credit this thesis to the contributions which Mr. Stephen has re- ceived from evolutionism. It goes back — not to search more deeply — as far as Comte, who had no patience with idle inquiries into the origin of species. But in Mr. Stephen's mind it is lighted up and vivi- fied by modern evolutionary science — especially by the doctrine of a " moving equilibrium " between organism and environment. In the next place, Mr. Stephen may be said to combine these two positions in a syllogism, which issues in a third proposition by way of conclusion. Since all organisms strive after maximum efficiency, and since society is an organism,2 society also will strive for maximum efficiency. But — here to a cer- tain extent hypothesis begins — we may very well un- derstand moral rules as the outcome of this striving, or as the formulated conditions of maximum social ef- ficiency. The effort or nisus of the social organism has broken into consciousness in the individual mem- bers of society in the shape of moral commands or ideals of duty. A Darwinian doctrine of competing organisms is scarcely if at all found in Mr. Stephen. 1 p. 32 ; cf. also p. 1 10. 2 We shall see, however, presently that Mr. Stephen prefers a slightly different phraseology. CHAP, x "SCIENCE OF ETHICS" 107 So far as he thinks of any competition, the competi- tion is rather between the claims of the individual man and the claims of society. Each man is an or- ganism, immersed in the thickest of the struggle for existence, striving to do the best for himself. But then, society too is an organism ; and it also strives ; and its precepts cut across the blind self-interest of the natural man — checking it, modifying it, perhaps overruling it. Morality then — it is a hypothesis, but a strong one — consists in the recognised and approved conditions of social efficiency. There are, however, some quali- fications. So far as social well-being implies indi- vidual physical well-being, we do not (unless in a secondary degree) count the observance of such con- ditions among moral duties. It is not a moral act to eat when one is hungry — it is natural. Nature se- cures our doing that ; society need not trouble about the matter; and morality — which is the voice of society, protecting the interests of the race — if it speaks of prudential regard to one's health and inter- ests as a duty, gives prudence a comparatively low position among the virtues. Whatever is the out- come of organic natural impulse forms rather a pre- supposition than a part of morality. Further — consulting, as I understand him, the usage of lan- guage— Mr. Stephen is inclined to confine the epi- thet " moral " to altruistic actions. Ordinary conscious action in one's own interest seems independent of the moral spur. It seems to stand almost, though not quite, on the same level with natural instinct. But with these two qualifications — that morality does not include those conditions of social efficiency which are taken care of by instinct, nor yet those in which the 108 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n social demand coincides exactly with the promptings of rational self-interest — Mr. Stephen holds that morality means the law of the social weal, or the con- ditions of maximum social efficiency. The law of nature is summed up in one terse injunction : " Be strong ! " The law of morality is similar : " Let society be strong ! " And social strength or welfare is found to lie in the individual virtues of courage, temperance, and truthfulness, along with the more directly social or altruistic virtue which is sometimes hailed as "justice," and again as "benevolence," but which, in every case, takes as its direct and supreme rule the highest interests of society, or the welfare of other persons. Mr. Stephen explains this conception of morality by the aid of the idea of type. A type in each class, apart from extrinsic and accidental tests, is that which attains maximum efficiency. The most moral human society is the most efficient or most prosperous human society. Here then Mr. Stephen has found a second answer to the question, How can empiricism speak of morally better and morally worse ? The first answer was provisional; the moral consciousness is a fact, and we accept its utterances as approximately trust- worthy. The second answer goes deeper. Morality is not something externally added to social life, as a necklace or a posy of flowers may form a slight addi- tion to the graceful dress of a beautiful woman. Morality is simply the perfect performance of social functions, like the glow of health upon a beautiful countenance. Therefore human life in society points to perfect morality as its own typical perfection in the way of vitality or of health. And here we see what CHAP, x "SCIENCE OF ETHICS" IOQ biological evolutionism has done for Mr. Stephen. It is not indeed strictly necessary for his argument. There might be evolution in human society, with the moral law as its ideal goal, even if there were no evo- lution of species in the infra-human world. The "typical bow" which is "felt out" might point us to Mr. Stephen's conception of morality as the true type of our own social being, even if there were no evi- dence that "the animal . . . feels itself out."1 But there would not be the same trace or hint of authority in Mr. Stephen's evolutionary interpretation of morals, did we not believe in the origin of species by a process of evolution. Morality is vindicated when we see that all nature, or all animated nature, toils upwards, and that our goal, if not as individuals, yet as a race, is moral goodness. The morally good society is the typically human society ; the morally good individual, so far as he is good, is qualified for membership in that society. Here, however, a difficulty arises. Mr. Stephen renews his warning against a doctrine of absolute or ideal ethics. The type is a real type in the actual present, a type constantly modifying itself as the environment alters or as the conditions of struggle change. Yet on the whole the broad out- lines of the type are fixed ; the cardinal virtues are recognised on all hands, very nearly as they have been blocked out by Mr. Stephen ; and we may say in general terms that morality represents the human ideal — the demand addressed by the race to every individual. Here as elsewhere, Professor Alexander gives us a more extreme position on the lines of Mr. Stephen's tentative suggestions. 1 P- 79- IIO FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n It is necessary to emphasise one other feature in Mr. Stephen's evolutionary view of ethics. He insists that, in such a society as that of mankind, the organic whole may change while the individual or- ganisms are unchanged. In a somewhat obscure passage he contrasts this most complex case, ex- emplified in human society, with simpler cases, in which the individual organism and the social or- ganism are modified simultaneously. One cannot help thinking that the whole distinction is a piece of very doubtful philosophy. What Mr. Stephen wishes to bring out by it is the fact that the social organism exerts its influences by the spiritual forces of thought and language, apart from any necessary reference to physiological change. So completely is Mr. Stephen indifferent to the moral applications of Mr. Spencer's view — which he shares 1 — as to the origination of apparently intuitive perceptions. Morality is evolved, according to Mr. Stephen's statement, not at all by means of a growing stock of innate moral sentiments, though he believes in these, but essentially by a super-organic process in the region of human culture and intercourse. Train- ing makes the man. Physiologically there is as good as no difference between the civilised and the savage. This is proved by the fact that the infant child of civilised parents, if stolen by savages, will grow up in the likeness of the savage race, and that the child of savages, if reared among the influences of civilisa- tion, will make a very fair average citizen. Dif- ferences there may be, which will hold their ground, even when transplanting has occurred and the new 1 English Thought in i8th Century, i. p. 56. CHAP, x " SCIENCE OF ETHICS " III environment has done its work ; but these (or so I understand Mr. Stephen) are insignificant in com- parison with the broad fact that every child or man is a human being, homo sapiens, and therefore a moral being ; that each child or man is merged in the community where he has grown up and takes on its colour. Now one is fully prepared to agree with the positions here laid down. A man's a man for a' that ; there is a vast moral unity in the human race. But Mr. Stephen's mode of stating his posi- tion seems highly dubious. Anthropologically or physiologically, man may be simply man, neither more nor less ; but we were speaking of sociology, were we not? If the social organism is changed, are not the constituent individuals changed, socio- logically? Strange metaphysical subtlety of em- piricists, if this is to be denied! To remind us that the members of society are physiologically un- changed is beyond the mark. To point out that civi- lised citizens would have been savages, if reared among savages, is again beside the mark. The ques- tion is not what they might have been, but what they are. Mr. Stephen may settle it with other authorities whether or not it is true that the "innate faculties of a modern European differ little from those of the savages who roamed the woods in prehistoric days."1 Be that as it may, the educated faculties of a modern European differ greatly from those of a con- temporary or prehistoric savage after his fullest savage training. Else the two societies could not differ. Mr. Stephen thinks he is offering us a contrast between the individual human organism 1 p. 102. 112 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n and the social organism ; he is only marking the contrast between two distinct sciences, sociology and biology. So far, then, we have got the following account of ethics from Mr. Stephen ; it is the law of the social weal imposed, essentially by precept and example, upon individuals. But there still opens before Mr. Stephen another problem. How does the individual come to receive and obey the aforesaid law ? And why should he do so ? He is led to care for others — so we may put Mr. Stephen's view — by sympathy. To be aware of pain — of another's pain — is to be more or less pained oneself ; to be aware of pleasure — another's pleasure — is to have a pleasing object of contemplation, and thus to be oneself more or less pleased. Two harps stand near each other, you strike a chord upon one, the other takes up the sound — that is a picture of the origin of moral feel- ing as Mr. Stephen states it. If any one is inacces- sible to these secondary emotions, evoked by primary emotion on the part of his fellows, his intellect is at fault; he cannot have clearly understood that they are really suffering or really happy. It follows that he is an " idiot," says Mr. Stephen. Now, sympathy is a vague and ambiguous word. If you say that morality rests upon sympathy you may mean almost everything that the moralist can require, or you may mean hardly anything at all. Mr. Stephen, like Adam Smith I take it, means very little indeed. Morality rests upon a rooted psychological incapacity for clearly distinguishing between meum and tuum. It would seem perfectly open to the selfish man to retort the charge of idiocy against moralists of Mr. CHAP.X "SCIENCE OF ETHICS" 113 Stephen's type. "Idiot yourself," the bad man might say, with great force. For indeed there is nothing so incommunicable and purely personal as mere pleasure or mere pain. And moral sympathy, which makes us partners with one another in all things, is very far removed from automatic prompt- ings or illusions as to the limits of personality ; it does not fall below clear thought, but includes it and goes beyond it. Love is a relation of person to person, and the keen pang of love is not due to any vague apprehension, " What ! there is suffering about, is there?" but to the dreadful consciousness, " He is in pain ! Precisely he ! Not I, but he ! That is the maddening thought ! " Yes, and there too lies the ennobling experience. The further question, " Why should I yield ? why care for others ? " receives the answer, " Generally in the long run it pays in pleasure to oneself to do so ; but sometimes, we must admit — in unfortunate cases, or where there is too lavish generosity — self- sacrifice means a heavy nett loss." And with that the science of ethics, as conceived and worked out by Mr. Stephen, confesses itself bankrupt. The point has come at which the question of the justi- fication of the moral judgment can no longer be thrust aside. Defined at first as social requirement, duty is now tested from the point of view of the in- dividual consciousness; when a gulf discloses itself between the individual life and the social whole. We live in an irrational world ; for our nature craves and postulates happiness ; and, although sometimes when we deserve it we get it, yet often we have to do without. Better look facts in the face ! There 114 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n is no more to be said. The timid man will obey morality as a sort of insurance policy : he will be moral on the chance that immorality may be punished. But often the bold man will play a recklessly speculative game — heavy risks, great profits. If he succeeds, how can you prove to him that he chose wrongly? The "idiot" may have been quite right from his own point of view. So much for the " Science of Ethics " ! The Christian, too, admits that our moral nature lays down great postulates, to which experience does not always conform. But we look to the future for the recom- pense of reward — not " so much pleasure for so much goodness," but a larger life, and the "wages of going on and not to die." It will clear our thoughts if we compare Mr. Ste- phen with his predecessors. First, with Comte. In some respects Mr. Stephen seems to be the legitimate heir of Comte, especially in regard to the biological appeal. Stephen's think- ing is guided throughout by the biological analogy, and he is able to throw fuller light upon it by the modern evolutionary conception of infinitesimal changes which maintain a moving equilibrium. Like Comte again, and unlike Spencer, he definitely iden- tifies morality with the claim of society upon the individual in contrast with all individual claims or wishes. But here the likeness to Comte ceases. First of all it is perhaps significant that Mr. Stephen refuses to speak of a social organism, preferring the more indefinite phrase, social tissue. That points us to the individualism which lurks in the background CHAP, x "SCIENCE OF ETHICS" 1 15 of his mind, — to his impending reassertion of the cells versus the organism, — to his postulate of per- sonal pleasure as an ultimate test. But there is a more immediate difference from Comte, in Mr. Stephen's distrust of sociology and of all forms of authority. Keeping that in mind, we might almost say that Mr. Stephen uses the biological analogy to reach sociological but not moral truth. With Comte sociology was the new ethic ; or, at the lowest, soci- ology, the science of corporate action, was the neces- sary basis of ethics as the science of individual conduct. Mr. Stephen, however, speaks contemptuously of the attainments of sociology. He thinks it scarcely a science, and values its standpoint merely as a step- ping-stone to a new statement of ethics, in which the biological analogy defines rather than justifies the moral law. It follows that the biological appeal has not the moral or quasi-moral weight which it had with Comte. Nothing takes its place. The appeal to consequences admittedly breaks down. In fact there is a marked absence of authority in ethics as presented by Stephen. Comte says, "You are members one of another, be loyal members of the social whole." Stephen says, " Social tissue requires you to do so-and-so, and of course you are very de- pendent on the social tissue ; still, you have a centre of being in yourself, and there is always the possibility left that it may pay you to defy society ; very rarely indeed will it do so, but sometimes, no doubt, it will, if you are unsocial enough, idiotic enough, bad enough." Comte allots no sphere at all to the individual, while Stephen, like other hedonists, gives him a sphere, but makes it fall outside of morals. What is moral is not Il6 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n personal, but social. What is personal is not moral, but hedonistic. As compared with Spencer, Stephen also deals mainly with one great harmonious process of evolu- tion, though with him it is purely biological — either the maintenance of health, or the fuller unfolding of life ; and he does not trouble us with definitions in terms of matter and motion, or with hymns of praise to complexity. '"'" Spencer's second great ideal, that of balance between egoism and altruism, is dismissed by Stephen as a Utopian dream; but he would dearly like to lay hold of it, if he dared, for he is as much a hedonist as Spencer; and, in the absence of perfect righteousness even from Utopia, Mr. Stephen's whole moral world lies at the mercy of chance. On Mr. Spencer's third ideal, that of political and social laissez faire, Mr. Stephen finds no occasion to ex- press an opinion in his own more purely ethical treatise. J Next, if we contrast Mr. Stephen's positions with those of Darwin, or rather with those suggested by Darwin's views, and worked out later in their ethical and social bearings by other writers, we observe an almost entire absence of any doctrine of struggle for existence. Evolution is accepted in the Darwinian sense, but little or no reference is made to the Dar- winian theory of the conditions of evolution. That remains true even in regard to the few passages where Mr. Stephen in a sense Darwinises, speaking not of one human social tissue, but of diverse forms of tissue. These various tissues may be thought of as competing with each other, but are hardly recog- nised as struggling for life, and as either dying out CHAP, x "SCIENCE OF ETHICS" 1 1/ or else covering the whole field. If Mr. Stephen has a struggle in view at all it is that between morality and selfishness, social tissue and personal organisms, society and individuals — a dreary conflict, to which there seems no discernible limit on the farthest horizon. Finally, how does he differ from -Utilitarianism ? There is one very important practical difference. The Utilitarian, as a moralist or spiritual director, defines right and wrong, and urges men to define right and wrong, by a computation of visible results, in the light of the present tastes and faculties of liv- ing men. Mr. Stephen on the other hand, when he speaks as an expert upon moral points, — as a con- sulting moral physician, or the giver of "counsel's opinions " in morals, — Mr. Stephen remembers what evolutionism has taught him, that the race has changed and is changing. Therefore he keeps in mind the probability that results, which we think highly advan- tageous, may be judged very differently by a future society when it measures them by its new standards and altered tastes. And therefore Mr. Stephen appeals to recognised moral duties and maxims as guides to social welfare. He distrusts the most acute calculation of the consequences which we can foresee. Morality has been evolved on the lines of social ad- vance, and points us on to the true line of further progress. Not pleasure, but health or vitality, is to be our test. Now this is good and wholesome teach- ing, far better than hedonism, however universalistic. But with Mr. Stephen this is all a technical thing. He speaks thus as a moralist to moral minds. But, when he speaks as a man to individual men, there is Il8 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART n instantly a relapse into hedonism, and that of the selfish sort. Granted the moral judgment — given a soul devoted to the social weal — Mr. Stephen offers vigorous and pointed encouragement, and dis- suades one from being argued out of obedience to conscience. But, if the moral judgment be disputed, and if any soul prefers his own private weal, Mr. Stephen gives no help. To call selfish men " idiots " merely because they distinguish meum from tuum is not helpful. Tastes differ — that is the last word on these questions, if we adopt Mr. Stephen's premises. One thing more we might be tempted to inquire, — How far is this whole mode of looking at morals true and serviceable ? But hitherto we have raised no such issue, and it would hardly be wise to discuss it at this particular point. Only so much we may say : if the community is to be the authority in ethics it must not be narrowly identified with any external society; and that which it lays down as duty must not be merely what is socially convenient — still less, what is convenient for society and costly to the individual ; duty must include absolute and ideal elements, whose fulfilment is quite as much for the interest (in the true sense) of the individual as for that of society. But, granted some such deeper view of society, it may be useful to have a statement of morality as the single or continuous human ideal, and to have this in terms of biology. It is well, too, that one of the biologising moralists should emphasise, not obscure subconscious possibilities of organic change, but the knowable influences of human education and historic culture. We shall quote Mr. Stephen for this at a later point. PART III DARWINISM, OR STRUGGLE FOR EXISTENCE CHAPTER XI " DARWINISM IN MORALS " — MISS COBBE'S PROTEST Darwinism may be applied to morals by analogy — Or, as here, by explaining man's evolutionary origin — Miss Cobbe attacks Darwin's explanation of the rise of morals out of intelligence plus sympathy — And the hypothetical palliation of murder — Little trace of natu- ral selection in Darwin's ethical statement — Darwin's analysis may be accepted, not his view of reason IT is not necessary again to recapitulate the lead- ing points of Darwinism. Nor is it desirable to pause at present in order to weigh some very grave metaphysical objections 1 to the terminology and con- ceptions with which Mr. Darwin went to work. We are more concerned to ask how Darwinian ideas have 1 Urged with great force by Dr. Hutchison Stirling, and incident- ally brought out with masterly power in Mr. George Sandeman's Prob- lems of Biology. Mr. Sandeman's statements go far to convince one that Darwin's theory is only a possible way of putting the process of evolution for purposes of study, and by no means an account of the way in which the process actually took place. It might\ia.ve. happened just so, by random shots, and constant weeding, in the course of end- less time. But did it? Possibly Mr. Sandeman himself might prefer a more sweeping verdict. See further in chapter xvii. 119 I2O FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in affected the theories of morals or of society which follow biological lines. Now plainly there is an ambiguity here. In the previous chapters,' for the most part, we have been dealing with a scientific analogy, — consciously lifted out of one region of thought and introduced into another, — coming no doubt with a great deal of authority, but still presenting itself to view, and con- tinuing to be regarded, as a foreign visitor. We shall still find such a course followed in some instances by writers who are employing Darwinian clues and modes of thought. The doctrine of struggle for existence may be applied to other things besides plants or animals, — to competing states, or types of society, or types of ethical thought. But there is a nearer way in which Darwinism may bear upon our problems. Man himself as an organism is brought within the range of Darwinian theories. In connection with the assertion of man's descent from brute races, fresh light — of a lurid kind, as many will think — is made to fall upon the problems of ethics; and questions as to social origins will run back into questions regarding human origin by pro- cess of evolution. When the world first heard of "Darwinism in Morals " from Miss Frances Power Cobbe, it was to this latter bearing of the Darwinian theories that she called attention by a resonant protest. Darwin — like Leslie Stephen after him, but with a distincter reference to animal ancestors of the human race — explained morality from sympathy, and from the interests of the species. In particular, he laid it down that the social instinct, with intelligence added CHAP. XI "DARWINISM IN MORALS" 121 to it, would sufficiently explain the origin of moral ideas. This shocked Miss Cobbe's intuitionalist pre- possessions ; she could not bear to see moral ideas analysed, as if they were compounded of other, and these non-moral, elements. But above all, Miss Cobbe was aroused to natural indignation by Darwin's sug- gestion, a prop os to the action of bees in killing off drones, that, if the welfare of our species had re- quired, under any conditions, a similar practice of murder, then the human conscience would undoubt- edly have ranked murder not among vices but among virtues. None of these positions seems to be peculiarly connected with the theory of evolution by a process of struggle for existence. They seem to belong rather to evolutionism in ethics than to Darwinism in ethics; although, as positions put forward by Darwin, they naturally and quite fairly received the title under which Miss Cobbe attacked them. Still, any thinker who believed in the continuity of life between man and beast, might, if he pleased, formu- late similar positions to Darwin's. On the other hand, it is perfectly plain that such positions are incompatible with old-fashioned intuitionalism. It is equally plain that the new fable of the bees is also (like the old one, as generally understood) incompatible with loyalty to morals. But the attempt per se to deduce morals from intellect plus social sym- pathy is not to be so summarily rejected. It is time to recognise that old-fashioned intuitionalism, with all its honest loyalty to the truth and its essential right-heartedness, is weak, as philosophers say, for- mally, and is no longer fit to sustain the " struggle 122 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in for existence " against subtler theories. The whole method of building up mind from simple elements is an illusion, whether practised by intuitionalists or by naturalistic schools of moralists. There is no primitive atom in mind. Every element implies every other. If it is true in biology that the whole is prior to the parts, how much more in psychology ? Moral judgments are not proved to be artificial, or secondary, or subordinate, if it is shown that they can be interpreted in terms of man's social nature. Man is moral because he is social: yes, very true; but we are no less entitled to read the proposition from the other end, and to affirm that man is social because he is moral. He is both social and moral in a higher sense than the brute races. We must not assume that the earliest stages in development show us the nature of an organism better than the later stages. A frog is not an effete tadpole ; on the contrary, a tadpole is an immature frog. And so man's moral nature is not a corollary or appendage of brute sociability ; on the contrary again, animal sociability is a dim and imperfect prophecy of human morality and human society. Of course, if Darwin's doctrine of reason were un- impeachable, it would be idle to challenge his moral philosophy while admitting his view of the descent of man. But we find his philosophical basis very insecure. Darwin assumes that instinct is given as a fixed datum ; rational consciousness, when it super- venes, works out plans and methods, but does nothing to revise or remodel the inherited aim. Instinct plus reason form a mechanical sum in addition. Reason is a calculating faculty pure and simple. Instinct CHAP, xi "DARWINISM IN MORALS" 123 remains what it was in the brute nature (social instinct for example, as the germ of morality) ; it now wields an instrument of incomparably greater power, but its own nature and its aims are unaltered. We shall have to give further study to this view of reason later on. Here we must simply affirm the counter position, that reason transforms and revolutionises everything. In this case as in many others, develop- ment means transformation. A man is not an ascidian, even if he is descended from one. Nor is human morality the pursuance of animal sociality with the resources of human intellect. No ; it is a new aim, as well as a new method ; on the theoretical side, reason; on the practical side, morality, strictly and properly so-called. As such, it has suppressed, is suppressing, and will suppress those evil things — evil at least between man and man, if not between beast and beast — which instinct tolerates or fosters. If, however, we take this view of the meaning of evolution, there seems no reason why the abstract formula of " Darwinism in Morals " should be fatal to the higher interests of mankind, or to the basis of Christian faith. CHAPTER XII DARWINISM IN POLITICS I BAGEHOT Applies Darwinism by analogy — Evolution transforms imperceptibly — By nerve tissue in our case ; but nothing depends on this assertion of use-inheritance by Bagehot; it is a mere illustration — ~NQl ethno- logical, but political questions — Problems both of progress and of differentiation — ist, Custom as the remedy for primitive wildness in the " fit " — Criticism — 2nd, Customs winnowed by the test of war — 3rd, Free discussion — Race blending, etc., as minor factors — Three limitations on the Darwinian principle in Bagehot's appli- cation of it. [Note B. On Professor Ritchie's Darwinism and Politics — Incon- sistency between the different essays — One interesting hint] THE next important application of Darwinian notions to social questions is found in Walter Bage- hot's Physics and Politics -, — a little book full of interest on every page, and still alive with sugges- tions after twenty-five years. It is or seeks to be truly Darwinian, dealing, as the title-page tells us, with "inheritance" and " natural selection," and trying to "apply them to political society." The author is profoundly impressed, first of all, with the transforming power which science attributes to evolutionary change. Things become absolutely different from what they were. Nay more ; this is true not merely of some things but of all. Every- thing is in motion. And therefore everything has 124 CHAP, xii DARWINISM IN POLITICS: BAGEHOT 125 become, in the light of modern science, "an antiquity." Speaking more strictly of human or social evolu- tion, Mr. Bagehot makes a very strong statement of the part presumably played by nerve tissue in render- ing such evolution possible. No one, he thinks, will be able to understand evolution in history, if he has not this material basis of evolution before his eyes. In other words, we have here an act of adhe- rence to Spencer's position — to Spencer's even more than Darwin's — against attacks such as have more recently been made by Weismann. For we have here not merely an assertion of the inheritance of acquired qualities, but an assertion of the physical inheritance of the results of mental processes. Further, we find Bagehot here emphasising an element which Leslie Stephen — though apparently believing in it — was content to drop out of sight all through his ethical treatise. Further still, we observe that for the moment Bagehot is not transferring Darwinian ideas to a new sphere, and asking how they apply there, but rather showing us how politics are influenced by Darwinism in its direct bearing upon the physical basis of mind. Man is a political animal, but he is primarily an animal. We cannot appreciate how his politics evolve unless we have formed just ideas of the process by which he himself evolves. Still, in all this, Bagehot is only preparing the way for his special contribution, which consists rather in extending the biological analogy than in claiming a wide range for biology proper. In point of fact, he might drop out this illustration altogether ; he might surrender his strong belief in the inheri- 126 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in tance of experience via the nervous system ; and yet the main lines of his book need not be changed. All through the discussion his problem, as he conceives it, has these two sides, physiological and polit- ical, but he declines to deal directly with the physio- logical questions involved. How have nations been differentiated ? We assume an original unity of the human race; from whence then the differences? Bagehot is to deal with the minor causes, which are mainly political. Beyond and behind their range, other very obscure causes must have been at work to separate, not nation from nation, but race from race; to differentiate negroes or Mongolians from white men ; presumably we might add, to differen- tiate Aryans from Semites. But, apart from a single reference to views held by Mr. A. R. Wallace, Bagehot does not enter upon this question at all. Granted race evolution, he asks how political evolu- tion proceeds. Do we encounter in it the workings of inheritance and natural selection? If so, what forms do they take? But even within the political region two problems are entangled together — if, indeed, I ought not rather to say that there are two different ways of conceiving the one political problem. This double- ness of aspect or of parts is embarrassing ; yet it is a difficulty we often encounter as we follow evolution- ary discussions, especially those which bear upon man. Does evolution mean progress, or does it simply mean differentiation ? By wedding " Physics," i.e. biology, and " Politics," are we seeking to explain the cause of political changes or rather of political improvement? Parts of Bagehot's book deal with CHAP, xn DARWINISM IN POLITICS: BAGEHOT I2/ the latter point, especially his closing chapters. On the other hand, are we simply trying to explain the origin, from one common stock, of the immensely divergent assemblage of national constitutions which history records or living experience manifests ? This question is also in his view. Perhaps we ought to say that he wishes to study both phases of his theme, but that he is chiefly interested in the laws of true progress. Before history, he tells us, there was a prehistoric age, before morals, a non-moral age. If man was created, he must have had everything to learn. If man was evolved from purely animal forms — this Bagehot seems to regard as probable, but as non- essential to his argument — there must have been an interregnum between the time when instinct guided action and the time when reason became effective. Instinct on the whole secures safety, but reason weakens instinct, and custom, which is the equivalent of instinct at a higher grade, which is the earliest and most important safeguard of rational beings, must have been very slowly and very gradually for- mulated. Primitive savages were like modern savages in almost all their defects ; they were ignorant, capri- cious, passionate ; but their minds cannot have been " tattooed over with customs " like the minds of their remote posterity, the savages of to-day. While civil- ised man is social, primitive man, according to Bage- hot, was a being no longer guided by animal instinct, but imperfectly human, and very hard to break to the sway of society. Most men were wild; many races were purely wild ; and the vital problem during the emergence of society was to secure the formation 128 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in of a " cake of custom " which might keep savage nature in check. Good custom or bad might serve ; the quality of the custom was a secondary though doubtless very important point ; its existence was the main thing. "Any sort of government was better than npne at all." But in this, as in so many matters, the first step was much the hardest. Once he had laid aside his primitive rudeness, the imitativeness of man made everything easy. Imitation continued old customs, imitation diffused attractive novelties. It was thus both a conservative and a progressive force, but it was oftenest at work in the service of inherited usage. Here then were the factors of social order — custom and imitation. Once the race became politi- cal it developed an overwhelming power of conserva- tism. Custom had made men what they were ; they dimly felt this and worshipped every custom with equal enthusiasm, the worst no less than the best. But indeed isolation was useful in early days. Jealousy of novel or foreign ways was a wise pas- sion while the social type was too weak to bear contact with other types. In the way of comment or criticism one need only here remark that almost everything in this eulogy of custom turns upon Bagehot's theory of the unsocial wildness of the first men, or, as he tends to translate that conception, on the theory that, when man was evolved, instinct went off duty before reason and custom came on duty. Probably that proposition is disputable. And the whole attempt to affirm how reason must have proceeded in entering a world that knew it not is perhaps an attempt to tran- scend the limits of possible knowledge, more CHAP, xii DARWINISM IN POLITICS: BAGEHOT 1 29 truly so than many things which have been thus described. Custom being established, the next question to be faced is, how the cake of custom may be broken and progress inaugurated. Custom, and the rough natural selection of early ages, ensure stability ; they are the factors in social statics; but what are the factors in social dynamics ? For a long time the greatest selecting agency is war. Military nations prevail over those which are less effective upon the field of battle, and to a large extent imitation gradually diffuses the principles of the higher and conquering civilisation among the vanquished. For in a sense the conquering civilisation is higher. Reflection shows us that, up to a certain point, the best man wins in the fierce competition of war. The military virtues are correlated to other virtues besides conquest. Beyond a certain point, however, progress is not secured. War tests and develops the military virtues, but it does nothing to hinder the heavy weight of custom from crushing out the finer possibilities of human nature. On the contrary, as we know from Mr. Spencer, militarism is the natural ally of autocracy and of reaction ; it calls for a blind obedience. Therefore, to end this paragraph as we began it, we are called on by Bagehot to notice how very many civilisations have become stagnant; how very few have been the instances of progress ; how many beginnings that promised well have suffered a speedy arrest. In the same spirit another distinguished writer, Sir Henry Maine, has taught us that the bar- barian inroads may have been needed to save Europe from the fate of China. These positions are memor- 130 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m able in view of what we shall hear from Mr. Benjamin Kidd (speaking on the authority of Professor Weis- mann) that for every organism the choice lies between struggle, victory, and progress on the one hand, and continuous retrogression on the other hand. China has at least worn the appearance of stagnation for many ages. China seems to have evaded Mr. Kidd's dilemma. But, if war has a limited power of selection, and effects a certain amount of progress, the decisive step has been due twice over to the influence of free discussion in the sphere of government. The habit of political debate in the Greek democracies, the same habit afterwards as a tradition of the Teutonic peo- ples, kindled and enflamed the mental activity of civilised men, till discussion, like a forest fire, had spread to all the material within reach. Democracy is not needful for this effect. The so-called Greek democracies were really petty aristocracies of slave- holders. You may have as high a franchise as you like, yet, if free discussion prevails within the privi- leged circle, then the emancipating force is at work. Mere oratory may not educate. The graceful oratory of the Red Indians dealt with methods, not with principles, and effected nothing towards progress in civilisation. But, when political discussion deals with great topics, it has a marvellously stimulating and educating effect on the mind. That has been the chief factor in social dynamics. That has twice broken the cake of custom. And now the intellect is fully awake, and progress itself has become a tradition of the western world. Jn subordination to these great factors Bagehot CHAP, xii DARWINISM IN POLITICS: BAGEHOT 131 notes others. For example, he dwells on the impor- tance of the blending of races. Such mixture, it is thought, frequently improves the breed, and so leads to evolutionary progress. But even if it results in no improvement — or even if it tends to deterioration — it may yield a new type, and so conduce to variety of result ; if not to progress, yet to differentiation. We take leave then of this most interesting little book with three remarks. First ; it does not yet show us Darwinism in relation to ethics or even in relation to sociology in the stricter sense, but rather in relation to politics. Now in politics there can be no question that we have before us a spectacle of competition — pre-eminently, but by no means solely, in the fierce rivalries of actual war. And so the application of Darwinian ideas in this region is unquestionably lawful, if a trifle obvious. Secondly ; in spite of his references to the nervous system, Bagehot assumes inheritance mainly by the psychical and political forces of imitation and custom. Thirdly ; he does not to any great extent connect the other side of politics — progress, social dynamics — with natural selection in the strict sense. Progress as well as stability rests upon imitation and upon the possibil- ity of loans in culture. To a certain extent progress rests upon war — but not upon wars of extermination ; not, therefore, on elimination of the unfit and survival of none but the fittest. Mainly progress is due to the habit of political discussion, and to happy circum- stances giving that habit great effect. In other words, Bagehot's social dynamics centre round a purely political idea. Not the biological analogy but special historical knowledge has been his guide. Darwin 132 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in has set him thinking, but Darwinism has not mastered or overmastered the course of his thought. This is not said by way of blame or disparagement, but in order that we may reach a precise view of the nature of Bagehot's contribution, and may understand how it differs from other contributions with which we have still to deal. NOTE B : On Professor Ritchie's " Darwinism and Politics " [Professor Ritchie's bright little book does not propose to apply Darwinism to the details of social life or history. It deals with the question whether the application holds good in principle — whether or not Darwinism really applies to politics. Unfortu- nately it is not easy to harmonise the teaching of the different essays. The bearing of the first essay is as follows : Whatever presumptions are established by a Darwinian view of the origin of man, there is no ground for believing that social progress necessarily implies struggle; reason has come in to change all things. But the drift of essays II. and III. is in quite a different direction : The analysis of evolu- tion by Darwinism is absolutely trustworthy, and may assuredly be extended to human society, " mutatis mutandis ! " This implies that reason has made only minute changes. Yet the first essay teaches that reason has equalised the efficiency of the two sexes, and again, that it has suspended the necessity for struggle. How much Darwinism is left if you elimi- nate struggle for existence ? There is one hint of some interest in essay I. — CHAP, xii "DARWINISM AND POLITICS" 133 that reason, as embodied in governments, may achieve a better economy of material than is done by [" nat- ural selection " or] laissez faire. But whatever the value of this hint, it is not Darwinian. And the title promises Darwinism ; and that is what we are study- ing at this moment. Some further remarks on Prof. Ritchie's positions will be found in chapters xvii. and xx.] CHAPTER XIII DARWINISM IN ETHICS I PROFESSOR ALEXANDER Fusion of idealism and naturalism — Moral judgments are facts, but the assertion of free will is absurd — Criticism; capricious; ignores the content of moral judgments and the germ of a system in them — Punishment grouped with dynamics ? — Statics are truly, though im- perfectly, moral — Goodness is a two-fold " equilibrium " — This doc- trine is enforced against other definitions — In the Dynamics equilib- rium is revealed as endlessly changing, and is called " compromise " — Ideals compete like organisms for survival — Criticism ; not (a) true Darwinian struggle, nor (£) true extinction — The new ideals are not wholly new — Ideals are complementary — So far as he Dar- winises he is false to morality PROFESSOR ALEXANDER'S Moral Order and Progress is a very full, interesting, and original discussion. Its character, as the sub-title indicates, is " an analysis of Ethical Conceptions." The general position of the author is that of one struck with the convergence of idealistic and naturalistic ethics in the light of evolu- tionism ; but, while coming himself from the camp of the idealists, Mr. Alexander is strongly inclined to seek a place in the left wing of the partially amalga- mated forces. All that is true or solid in idealist ethics is provided for, he thinks, in the biological scheme. As for intuitionalism, it may go packing ; there is no portion for it in the promised land of truth ; it is mere mischievous illusion. We have been told by some of Lord Beaconsfield's admirers that there CHAP. Xiii DARWINISM IN ETHICS: ALEXANDER 135 was a great unity throughout his career, in spite of all apparent change — he always disliked the middle classes. Against them he appealed variously to the nobles and the poor, to Tory and Radical instincts. So it is to be with the typical bourgeois philosophy of intuitionalism. Idealists and empiricists are to agree sweetly in destroying it. Its excellent intentions shall not excuse it one cruel blow, in view of its hopeless and irritating limitations. Having affirmed so strongly the competency of naturalism, Mr. Alexander has to face a question which, in our judgment, presses hard upon all natu- ralistic ethics. What room is there for ethics at all' upon the premises of naturalism ? What do we mean' by speaking of right and wrong, of moral good and moral evil, in a world of blind laws and mere facts and necessary processes? Mr. Alexander, like Mr. Stephen, faces the question and gives the same provisional answer. Primarily, we are dealing with acknowledged facts, viz. with those moral judgments which, as a matter of fact, are current. In the first instance, therefore, Mr. Alexander takes over moral opinion as he finds it, and, like Mr. Stephen, tells us he is concerned to analyse it rather than to verify it — to systematise it, as we might perhaps interpret, rather than to apply any more radical test. Self- consistency is indeed a legitimate test, though but a negative test of truth ; and if he had confined himself to requiring that morality should be self-consistent, coherent, systematic, Mr. Alexander could have done no possible injustice to the moral consciousness. As we read on, however, we feel that his provisional at- titude is very soon departed from. The utterances 136 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART ill of the moral consciousness are cut short — its dicta are edited or expurgated — with a view to securing harmony, not with each other, but with a determin- istic view of the universe borrowed from physics. True, the frontier of morality is extended a long way in certain directions. With admirable faithfulness Mr. Alexander reports that conscience passes its judgments on willed conduct — only on willed con- duct ; yet scarcely is this admitted when free will is mockingly expelled from the court unheard — free will, the one further truth which gives meaning and justification to our human habit of passing judgment only upon will. Why is free will exiled ? What pro- cured this order from the judge ? Morality did not require it; conscience asked nothing of the kind; victorious prejudice, and the tyranny of physical science, carried the day. That is not the way to provide our subject with a scientific frontier ! It results in a haphazard frontier — pushed far on, at one point, to suit the requirements of our own posi- tion, but then cut short to suit the requirements of other people across the border. Mr. Alexander is loyal to the psychological fact that we judge only willed conduct ; he takes care to report it accurately ; but what does he make of it ? Stated in isolation, is it not meaningless ? We see now in how restricted a sense moral facts are admitted by Mr. Alexander. The moral con- sciousness is allowed to bear testimony ; " AB is an ethical conception ; " " CD is an ethical conception " — but that is all. The authority of conscience is good to that extent — and not an inch beyond. If we ask the further question, what is the meaning of this CHAP, xm DARWINISM IN ETHICS: ALEXANDER 137 ethical conception AB ? conscience falters and grows embarrassed, or remits the matter for analysis to the laboratory of ethical science. From this point on- wards conscience is dumb, and Mr. Alexander acts as its proxy, or works up, as he judges good, the material with which it has furnished him. This criticism must not be misunderstood. We should not think for a moment of denying the rights and privileges of reflection, or of questioning its value. When moral opinion has done its utmost in the shape of healthy instinct, very much remains to be learned from the brooding meditative critic, who insists that we shall "see life steadily and see it whole," and who therefore brings our scattered thoughts into focus and tunes them together as a harmonious system. When that is faithfully done the moral philosopher is not the tyrant, but the minister atque interpres of con- science, carrying on its own work and giving it a higher perfection. He may indeed do more than this. He may provisionally call in question the teachings of conscience; he may subject them to tests ; provided he recognises that conscience has its own contributions to make to any final synthesis. But all this describes something very different from Professor Alexander's treatment of the subject. We do not blame him for revising or modifying the dicta of moral instinct, but for the kind of revision he prac- tises, — one which ignores that the process of inter- pretation is begun by conscience itself; one which lays down the law upon questions of morals in obe- dience to non-moral principles; one which treats the law thus laid down as decisive against the moral claims of free will. Conscience is invoked to supply 138 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m our author with facts for manipulation ; it is allowed to do nothing more. We cannot attempt to follow out Mr. Alexander's interesting discussion in detail. We can only name a few points which seem specially noteworthy, either for their own sake, or in connection with the history of the appeal to biology for human guidance. The subject is explicitly divided into two main parts — a statical and a dynamical ; moral order, and moral progress ; in obvious dependence upon Comte. One must be allowed to express a doubt whether names and things exactly correspond to each other here. As a point of detail, it is astonishing that punishment should be discussed under moral progress. If there is any obstinately statical element in the life of society, surely it is penal law, which maintains what has been reached, but is grimly indifferent to further progress. When saints or martyrs challenge a law that has been outgrown, or that is downright bad, there may of course be progress through the punishment they bear — thanks to them, not to the law. In itself the law does not even then make for progress. Its preoccupation, then as always, is sta- bility. And the ordinary victim of penal law is much more likely to be affected by atavism than by " the prophetic soul of the great world brooding on things to come." What is he doing in this galley ? When one passes from details to principles, Mr. Alexander's grouping of his materials looks more and more disquieting. He is really not contrasting moral order with moral progress ; he is giving us, first, an analysis of morality in the abstract, apart from ques- tions of progress, but secondly a theory of progress, CHAP, xm DARWINISM IN ETHICS: ALEXANDER 139 or rather of change, which sets morality at defiance. In the first half — thanks to his appeal, however strangely limited, to the moral consciousness — he is on moral ground ; the foundation is moral, whatever may be the character of the superstructure. In the second half he has moved off moral ground altogether. The first is a theory of morality from the inside, if not exactly from the heart of the subject ; the second is a theory of the changes in human opinion, a view taken from the outside of the moral process, and characterised by the airy indifference of the foreigner. In Part I. the analysis of the moral end leads to the result that goodness is an equilibrium, and one of a twofold order. For first, goodness is an equilibrium among the promptings or desires or actions of the individual ; and secondly, it is social, placing each man harmoniously with his fellows in an order of society. And this positive analysis is supported negatively by a destructive analysis of other views of the ethical end. To this extent therefore Mr. Alexander offers more proof in support of evolutionism in morals than Mr. Leslie Stephen gave us. Intuitionalism of course receives no attention. Intuitionalism holds that the good, like other primary elements of consciousness, cannot be decomposed, and neither can nor need be defined. It is hardly strange that one who is seeking a definition of the moral end should pass over such views in impatient silence. But, if intuitionalism is not discussed, a kindred position is faced when the definition of the end as perfection is brought under notice. This, says Mr. Alexander, gives no help. It carries us no further. Perfectly what should I be ? Perfectly good, of course. But I am asking you what 140 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m goodness is ! You have told me nothing ; . yqu have taken for granted the conception of goodness. Next, hedonism is discussed. Mr. Alexander dismisses as an over-refinement the idealist criticism, urged by T. H. Green or Mr. F. H. Bradley, according to which a sum of perishing pleasures is an impossibility. But he himself argues that pleasure cannot be the moral end, on the ground that there are ultimate irreducible qualitative differences between one kind of pleasure and another. Surely this does not seem altogether conclusive, especially since Mr. Alexander goes on to maintain that his own formula incorporates hedonism by insisting that some pleasures ought to be aimed at, viz. the pleasures of goodness. But there is no doubt that he is right, from the point of view of the moral consciousness, in holding that if pleasure enters into the end of [right] action, it cannot be pleasure as such but desirable pleasure, i.e. morally desirable pleasure. Lastly, Vitality is examined ; and Mr. Stephen is instructed that all that is true in this formula is cov- ered more exactly by the abstract formula, equilib- rium. So far as we have yet inspected this doctrine, it is evidently akin to the older evolutionism of Spencer or Leslie Stephen. One organism, or one set of forces, falls to be considered ; goodness is a harmony in the organism or among the forces ; badness is dishar- mony. At first sight one thinks that Mr. Alexander has materially improved upon Mr. Stephen's posi- tion. With Mr. Stephen, the individual man and the social whole fall violently asunder. But Mr. Alexan- der knows of a twofold moral equilibrium, applying alike to man and to society. Also one observes the CHAP, xin DARWINISM IN ETHICS: ALEXANDER 141 traces of Mr. Alexander's idealist schooling. For him, morality is still self-realisation or self -fulfilment. Unlike intuitionalists, he regards goodness, not as something added from outside to the natural motives of men, but as the correct working up of the raw material of character. It is true, Mr. Stephen, with his purely empiricist tendencies, has caught the same truth. But the truth deserves full acknowledgment wherever found. Assuming, as we are led to do, that the disorders in character are many, the order, only one, there seems no reason why we should quarrel with Mr. Alexander for speaking of equilibrium as the moral end, if he likes to do so. Following his own lead we might hint that a different formula did fuller justice to the real contents of the moral end ; but we should not condemn his formula as false. A very different light, however, is thrown back upon this definition from the second part of Mr. Alexander's treatise. In it we learn that there are many competing and successive types of morality — endlessly many. Goodness is not one, in contrast to the multitudinousness of evil and disorder. Goodness itself is no less protean. We must not hold that morality is the equilibrium of conduct ; each type of morality is an equilibrium. Without forestalling our discussion of the theory of moral progress, we notice now the bearing of this assertion, not simply on the theory of moral order, but on the very definition of morality. It had been proposed that we should de- fine morality as equilibrium. That definition is now robbed of its meaning. Is there any conduct at all which may not be said to seek an " equilibrium " — if only that of the simple equation, " Let me be on the 142 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m top and every one else below"? Matters are not improved but rather made worse when the word " compromise " slips out as a synonym for " equilib- rium." Is not almost everything a compromise — from some point of view ? The extortioner, the slayer of human lives, the cheat, " when he thinks of his opportunities," may, like Clive, be " astonished at his own moderation." You and I both claim some- thing ; half to me and half to you is a compromise ; but ninety-nine per cent to me and one per cent to you is also a compromise. I may even persuade myself that a hundred per cent to me is a com- promise, because I suffered you to get away with unrifled pockets. What possible light then is ob- tained by naming good conduct "a compromise"? A further objection remains. " Compromise " is the worst possible word for describing moral behaviour. Morality, as Mr. Alexander bears witness, imposes a law, and that law requires unconditional obedience. If we follow it out, our own nature will blossom into its true richness and fulness ; but for this the knife is as necessary as the watering can ; the path to moral self-development lies through self-sacrifice. Where is there room for talking of compromise in such a process ? The law indeed gives his due to each man, and also to each impulse. The "stern lawgiver" wears "the Godhead's most benignant grace " ; but no wrangling of private interests, no arbitrary delimitation of incompatible claims, will produce morality. In a word, morality involves order, equilibrium, peaceful settlement of competing claims ; but equilibrium — and still more plainly, compromise — neither includes nor leads to morality. CHAP, xiii DARWINISM IN ETHICS: ALEXANDER 143 Seek the higher and the lower will be added. Seek the lower — you lose all. We conclude therefore that Mr. Alexander's theory is neither true nor false but merely vague. The second half of the treatise deals with moral progress. The most interesting and novel part of this discussion is found in a doctrine laid down when treating of the origin of moral distinctions ; but, as there seems to be no reason why the doctrine should only be applied to the beginnings of moral progress, we shall treat it as covering the whole field. It sets before us a vision of competing moral ideals, and of the survival of the fittest. The process is illimitable ; there is no absolutely best ; every good, while it is valid, or to those for whom it is valid, is also the best ; and as continuous evolution and adjustment go on, the moral ideal must vary or be renewed in cor- respondence with the facts of human progress. This assertion is treated as showing us the prolongation of the Darwinian struggle into new and higher regions. If men do not habitually struggle against each other, to the point of extinction for the vanquished and solitary survival for the victor, ideals do so ; and the " creed outworn " succumbs, while the ideal which is up to date survives and predominates — for a season. So it always has been, so it always will be. Such constructions of ideas seem very much akin to primitive mythology. Here too we have a meta- phor, and here too the speaker does not know or does not remember that it is a metaphor, but treats it as a revelation of absolute scientific truth. The author uses most of the implications and inferences connected with Darwin's analysis, and uses them 144 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART ill with dogmatic confidence. He never fully inquires what limits attend their use. Of course, it is possi- ble to represent progress in thought as due to a com- petition between various types or ideals. Let us grant this in the fullest way. Such language is lawful ; it may be suggestive and valuable. But metaphors are treacherous things ; they leave out at least half the truth. Natural selection takes place, or is alleged to take place, through the struggle for existence, because there is not room for all to live and be nourished side by side. Every living organism cannot live out its full time and transmit its peculiarities to offspring. But what forbids moral ideals to exist side by side ? Truth to tell, they have done so in the past, and do so yet — in different lands, or even in one land — in different minds, or even in one mind. The struggle of ideals is much less keen than the biological strug- gle for existence, at least at starting, and in its lower stages ; afterwards its working may become swift and telling. Ideals compete against each other in human minds. They commend themselves not by any physical superiority, but by their attractiveness or by their truth. Secondly, there is a difference mentioned by Mr. Alexander himself. Defeat here, in the struggle of ideals, does not imply the extinction of the persons holding inferior moral conceptions. The ideals per- ish ; the persons who held them are usually con- verted to a higher way of thinking. Surely here we have an open admission that the struggle between ideals is not a struggle of the Darwinian order. Progress according to Darwin is dependent on the CHAP, xiii DARWINISM IN ETHICS: ALEXANDER 145 weeding out of the unfit. Progress according to Mr. Alexander is usually secured by a conversion from error to truth. It is a secondary result that errors disappear. And those who were formerly in the grasp of error do not die, but believe the truth and live. Yes, it may be said, the errors die. Is not that enough to justify the analogy ? Let us look then a little more closely at the alleged mechanism of moral progress. Variation constitutes, says Mr. Alexander, a new species or new ideal> before which, after a sea- son of struggle, old species or old ideals perish. Does not this statement ignore the fundamental continuity of life throughout all evolution ? The "new species " is an old species modified. The new ideal is not wholly new ; it is the fuller evolution or unfolding of the old, what Hegel called its truth. For of ideals above all things we may declare that they do not struggle blindly against each other, or exclude each other. They are not physically distinct things, mutually incompatible, mutually repulsive. Was there ever an ideal with a lower programme than that of the supreme Teacher, " Not to destroy, but to fulfil " ? The point may be illustrated by a quotation from John M'Leod Campbell: "An early member of the Society of Friends, writing to a brother who was a Roman Catholic, says, ' Your re- ligion and my religion must be the same, in so far as we have religion, for there is but one religion.' This true and deep word/' adds Campbell, " we are gradu- ally learning to understand." May we not even more confidently say the same thing of moral ideals ? There is but one ideal. The various forms in which, histori- 146 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in cally, the ideal presents itself are not distinct and rival species, but elements in the final synthesis — yearning aspirations after it — sketches, rough and rude at the best, yet instinct with life, and all representing one great pattern seen in the mount. Would an ideal kill another ideal if it could ? I do not ask, would an idealist kill an idealist ? That indeed is " another story " ; but does the ideal itself aim at extermination and destruction ? Mr. Alexander tells us that the rivals often blend in a " compromise." Surely, once again, the victory of truth is no compromise between opposite extremes, but something higher than either, in which all that is best in both the rivals lives on and flourishes. And the tertium quid at least may be due to a victory of truth. We conclude then that the application of Darwin- ism to competing moral ideals breaks down all along the line. For, first, what is described to us is not a process of natural selection by means of a struggle for existence ; and, secondly, so far as Mr. Alexander does assimilate moral ideals to competing organisms, he falsifies the facts. He has not really shown us an extension of Darwinian struggle into a higher region, but something radically different — something de- scribed by him more or less suggestively, but also more or less inaccurately, in Darwinian language. Progress by struggle — this morality thrusting down that morality and reigning in its stead — is not exhib- ited in the facts of history to any one who can look ever so little below the surface. Moral progress is much better described from Mr. Stephen's point of view as one great orderly evolution of human thought and life. Mr. Alexander sometimes uses similar Ian- CHAP, xni DARWINISM IN ETHICS : ALEXANDER 147 guage ; but if such language were meant in full earnest it would be necessary to cease speaking of the limitlessness or indefiniteness of moral change. We may be baffled and bewildered by the course of moral evolution. Many a time good but timid men have regarded change and even advance in moral conduct or ideas as pure wanton iconoclasm. But it was not so ; it was inwardly continuous with what went before. And, although philosophy itself must fail if it seeks to forecast the morality of a dis- tant future, yet the future form will grow out of the present, and, when it comes, men will see in it once more how wisely and how surely God fulfils Himself. To abandon that hope is to abandon morality and all that makes us human. CHAPTER XIV REACTION FROM DARWINISM; HUXLEY Reaction as to ethics — Due to the vision of strttggle and pain — Not sympathy, but justice is essential — It must suspend oirtright the cos- mic process — Older evolutionism (Greece, India) gave no guidance — Criticism ; nature and spirit are opposed — Yet connected, and reason fulfils the cosmic process by transforming it IT will readily be divined that it is in a special sense we connect the name of Huxley with reaction from Darwinism. From the time when he was converted to the new views, Huxley was perhaps their most brill- iant and successful advocate, both in scientific circles and as a populariser, speaking to the world of readers. Yet, in regard to ethics, he was continually restive. The Romanes lecture for 1893 is only the most delib- erate among many striking utterances of his, tending in that direction. His thesis runs to the following effect, that evolutionary science has done nothing for ethics ; that on the contrary men only become ethical as they set themselves against the principles embodied in the evolutionary process of the animal world. Far from regarding evolution as the master-key to ethics, Huxley insists that the two terms are irreconcilable. Plainly, Huxley has considered only one possible form of union between evolution and ethics. For him evolution means Darwinism ; the struggle for ex- 148 CHAP, xiv REACTION FROM DARWINISM: HUXLEY 149 istence which is believed to have dominated the plant and animal kingdoms. And for him the union of evolution with ethics means not analogy but identity ; it means that man, the individual organism, is held to become moral by succeeding in the struggle for exist- ence— a sufficiently startling paradox. Huxley makes no explicit reference to Spencer's formula, tracing a single harmonious process, right back to the primeval nebula and right on to moralised man. He is willing to generalise evolution as much as you please, but it seems to him that there is a seriously novel element introduced at one point in the process, cutting it as it were in two. " When the cosmopoietic energy works through sentient beings there arises among its other manifestations that which we call pain or suffering." And suffering is most intense in man, especially as he rises in the scale of civilisation, " under those condi- tions which are essential to the full development of his noblest powers." l Animal struggle runs on into human struggle, but such struggle is immoral. We must not wantonly add to the pain suffered by our fellows ; we must " let the ape and tiger die." The Spencerian formula — so we may read between the lines — makes no room for those elements which, to Huxley's mind, are of real moral significance. As for Comte's attempt to view social life as the evolution of one orderly and peaceful organism, or as to Mr. Leslie Stephen's gloss upon that attempt, or as to Pro- fessor Alexander's bloodless and well-nigh painless Darwinism in the shape of competing ethical types, Huxley says nothing. He cannot separate evolution from the cruel Darwinian struggle in its plain and 1 p. 10. 150 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m literal sense. He puts ethics and evolution as far asunder as the poles. We might almost style him a valuable if unexpected recruit to the cause of Miss Frances Power Cobbe. Darwin of course he knows by heart ; and Darwin's easy-going ethics felt none of his difficulties. How does he answer Darwin's proposal to deduce moral- ity from sociability plus intelligence ? Primarily, it would seem, by emphasising justice as the moral ideal rather than sympathy. Sociability might con- ceivably explain the rise of sympathy, but not of a sense of justice. "Wolves," he says, " could not hunt in packs except for the real though unexpressed understanding that they should not attack one another during the chase. The most rudimentary polity is a pack of men living under the like tacit or expressed convention; and having made the very important advance upon wolf society, that they agree to use the force of the whole body against individuals who vio- late it, and in favour of individuals who observe it." Out of this convention arises a sense of justice, within the human pack ; and justice is gradually deepened into righteousness. Now certainly such a conception of the moral ideal is not so easily fitted on to an evolutionary process as a more purely altruistic con- ception of goodness. Darwin thought sympathy or comradeship the chief point in ethics. Huxley swears by justice. He is tempted to call nature unjust ; he is sure that it is non-just. Once again, in a note, he returns to this point. Having by that time formulated the evil of cosmical nature not simply as pain, but as competition or struggle, he adverts to the fact that packs of wolves, CHAP, xiv REACTION FROM DARWINISM : HUXLEY 1 5 1 hives of bees, and all social or gregarious creatures have suspended the struggle within their own com- munity. "To this extent," he admits, "the cosmic process begins to be checked by a rudimentary ethical process, which is, strictly speaking, part of the former, just as the ' governor ' in a steam-engine is part of the mechanism of the engine." 1 This represents the sum total of the concessions which he would make to those like Messrs. Geddes and Thomson or the late Henry Drummond, who allege that Nature is not wholly red in tooth and claw, but that a principle of love is gradually disclosed and made predominant as we ascend the evolutionary scale. He grants that the wicked process of strug- gle is partially, slightly, very slightly checked, and checked by justice ; but, in the main, cosmical nature is full of struggle, and, from our human point of view, full of wickedness. The rest of the lecture does not add very much to these essential ideas. It verifies them by tracing former evolutionary thought in India and Greece. Indian wisdom regarded all things as embraced in an evolutionary process extending through aeon after aeon, and life upon life ; but it held this process to be downright bad and unhappy. Buddhism, its most characteristic expression, rested on a pessimistic view of the world ; such pessimism may have been one- sided, but its existence proves how little a belief in cosmic evolution did, in those days, to guide men as to their personal conduct. The cosmic process said "Live!" The enlightened one said "Extinguish yourselves ! " In Greece, the ethic of the Stoics was 1 p. 197- 152 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in alleged to be connected with their Pantheistic evolu- tionism ; but Huxley contends that it was really per- fectly independent of its speculative background; and that is very likely true. Coming down to modern times, he complains that discovery of " the evolution of ethics " has led men, in much confusion of thought, to preach an " ethics of evolution " ; whereas no such thing exists. Good of course has been evolved — but so has evil; beauty has arisen in evolution — and ugliness too ; what survives after struggle is " fittest to survive," but not necessarily best or noblest. Briefly, cosmical and ethical tendencies are opposite. We human beings have to develop our own ideas of justice; the bad, blind world can neither guide nor help us. In the past, struggle was of service when it gave man domain over the creatures (as theologians express it) — a curious hint. But now the remainders of struggle poison man's higher life. Perhaps this is seasonable discourse. After all, nature and spirit are different things, and, if philoso- phy drops below pantheism into downright material- ism and atheism, then too probably it will undermine morality. Nevertheless we must not exaggerate the difficulties of the case, or leap prematurely to the sorry conclusion that nature is in opposition to mo- rality. We are not obliged to rush into either extreme. Because we hesitate to recognise evolution as the key to ethics, we are not bound to regard evolution as anti-ethical. Huxley seems very one-sided when he draws a sharp contrast between the best and those fittest to survive. Bagehot and Mr. Leslie Stephen teach a different lesson. Among human societies it is probably fair to assume that in the majority of CHAP, xiv REACTION FROM DARWINISM: HUXLEY 153 cases the most moral are the strongest. So far as that is true of states or of individuals, the " blind " cosmic process does not oppose morality, but acts in its service. The difficulty is at least attenuated. A fuller answer to Huxley's perplexities regarding the moral bearings of evolution is to be found in a better view of reason. Morality is a new thing in the creation with the advent of rational man, yet not wholly new. It is the transformation and perfecting of animal ethics — not the simple inversion of the cosmic process. But it is a highly significant trans- formation. Pain also is transformed by the advent of reason. Even in the animal world, presumably, pain is outweighed by pleasure, Huxley himself being witness. In man, however, pain assumes a new mean- ing. It becomes an element in moral development. How then can the presence of pain brand the cosmos as evil? The kindred charge, that struggle is alto- gether evil from the moral point of view, will come before us again in the next and subsequent chapters ; we trust there are reasons for repelling that charge also. Lastly, we observe that a more intelligent con- ception of reason corrects Huxley's position as to the supremacy of man. Mastery of the animals is natural to mankind. It is no mere accident, due to man's share in the cruel cosmic struggle. It is man's right. It forms part of his equipment for that which lies before him, — the moral struggle to which the cosmic struggle gives place, the moral advance and moral achievement which are to crown the long and strange story of this earth. CHAPTER XV REACTION FROM DARWINISM : DRUMMOND'S " ASCENT OF MAN " His precursors — His sympathy for Spencer — His Comtist terminology — Seeks a biological basis for altruism — Corrects Darwin — Not like Miss Cobbe — Largely like Huxley — But seeks a fairer statement of the facts — Brings in a second biological function (out of three !), viz. reproduction — Wallace on the selection of reason — Leads up to the doctrine of "Arrest of the £ody" — Ci. Clelland on the human skull — Emphasis on maternity and weakness of human infant — Criticism; "egoism" and its struggle purely evil? — Or male sex with its justice? — Is domesticity = sociality? — Has Drum- mond shown a factor in progress? — A better philosophy claims all nature for God I HAVE chosen the Ascent of Man to represent the more conscious and definite reaction from unmodified or unbalanced theories of natural selection, not be- cause its author was the first or the only writer to champion such a reaction, but because he has given us its fullest statement, and because everything of Drummond's commanded at once a very wide popu- larity. For another reason he interests us, because he speaks as a Christian believer and thinker, — almost as a Christian apologist. He himself con- fesses obligations to many predecessors ; first, perhaps, to John Fiske, as we shall note in due course ; most largely and definitely to The Evolution of Sex by Professor Geddes and Mr. J. Arthur Thom- CHAP, xv REACTION FROM DARWINISM: DRUMMOND 155 son. These last writers, like Drummond, are con- sciously dissenting from Darwin, — consciously put- ting forward amendments to his statement of things, and not only to his statement of the basis of morals, but to his scientific formulation of the process of evolution itself. Morality is to be found somewhere in the region of sex. Struggle for life is a fact, but not the whole fact ; it is balanced by struggle for the life of others. Yet those who so speak are them- selves evolutionists, — themselves Darwinians. They accept struggle for existence as a great fact and po- tent cause of progress. They deny it to be the only fact ; and occasionally they are found denying that it is the only cause of progress ; but that topic is very lightly touched upon. Hence perhaps, in part, one's perplexity, when one seeks to estimate the value of this correction of Darwin's theories. With the wider Spencerian doctrine of evolution Drummond takes little to do. Yet he seems to as- sume its truth, or the truth of something of the same nature. His lyrical outbursts of praise at the thought of evolutionary science refer to something much more extensive than any view of the origin of species. Speaking of " evolution in general," he tells us that " Evolution is a Vision, . . . which is revolutionising the world of nature and of thought." When the workers of science had whispered the name " Evolu- tion," "henceforth their work was one, science was one, the world was one, and mind, which had discov- ered the oneness, was one." l Again somewhat later we read, " Nature in vertical section offers no break or pause or flaw." To study it in horizontal section 1 Ascent of Man, p. I. 156 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m "is to study a hundred unrelated sciences — sciences of atoms, sciences of cells, sciences of souls, sciences of societies ; to study it vertically is to deal with one science — evolution."1 All this points to Spencer's philosophy, or a cosmic philosophy of a similar type. Yet such a system is nothing but ornamental scenery, hung up in the background of Mr. Drum- mond's atelier. His references to it during his dis- cussion are of the slightest. Close to the end of his book 2 there is a whimsical attempt to trace the cosmic principle of love down into the inorganic world, and back to the nebulous cloud out of which natural law is said to have evolved all things. Chemical affinity is the supposed representative of the psychical principle of love, grouping the ele- ments of nature in close union! However, the author does not seem perfectly easy in his own mind as to this suggestion, or thoroughly in earnest with it. On at least two other occasions he quotes Spencerian language in a tone of discipleship. " The first work of evolution always is, as we have seen, to create a mass of similar things — atoms, cells, men; and the second is to break up that mass into as many different kinds of things as possible. Aggregation masses the raw material, collects the clay for the potter ; differentiation destroys the featureless monot- onies as fast as they are formed, and gives them back in new and varied forms." 3 Again : " Accord- ing to evolutional philosophy there are three great marks or necessities of all true development — Ag- gregation, or the massing of things ; Differentiation, or the varying of things; and Integration, or the 1 Ascent of Man, p. 59. 2 Ibid. p. 433. 3 Ibid. p. 320. CHAP, xv REACTION FROM DARWINISM: DRUMMOND 157 reuniting of things into higher wholes. All these processes are brought about by sex more perfectly than by any other factor known." 1 Except for these passing salutations, however, there is no appeal to the laws of physical or sub-organic evolution. We are bidden indeed follow nature; we are bidden throw ourselves into the current of evolution; but it is ani- mated nature that is to be our guide; the nature which Darwin studied will teach us rightly — if we a little readjust the formula in which Darwin summed up his results. Going back a step farther, from Spencer to Comte, we cannot but be struck with the extraordinary close- ness of discipleship manifested by Drummond. If Comte started the process of naturalistic study of duty under the flag of sociology, Drummond accepts the whole programme. The appeal to history dis- appears; with all his varied culture that was not in Drummond's line. But the appeal to biology stands ; the conception of altruism as a synonym for virtue stands firm ; the conception of sociology as an authori- tative science, growing out of biology, is accepted in so many words. " Every earnest mind is prepared to welcome" sociology, " not only as the coming science, but as the crowning Science of all the Sciences, the Science indeed for which it will one day be seen every other science exists. What it waits for mean- time is what every science has had to wait for, ex- haustive observation of the facts and ways of Nature. Geology stood still for centuries waiting for those who would simply look at the facts. . . . Sociology has had its Werners; it awaits its Huttons. The 1 Ascent of Man, pp. 336, 337. 158 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in method of sociology must be the method of all the natural sciences. It also must go and see the world making, not where the conditions are already ab- normal beyond recall, or where man, by irregular action, has already obscured everything but the con- ditions of failure, but in lower Nature which makes no mistakes, and in the fairer reaches of a higher world, where the quality and the stability of the progress are guarantees that the eternal order of Nature has had her uncorrupted way." 1 Most noteworthy perhaps, in comparison with Comte, is the attempt to justify the definition of virtue as " altruism " by some biological considera- tions. We shall speak more in detail of this pres- ently. If it should stand, would it not be another great stroke of luck for Comte ? or, ought I to say, a further vindication of his prophetic insight ? He did not foresee the evolutionary doctrine of the origin of species ; he even deprecated such theorising. Yet the inquiry has gone forward, and the doctrine has been promulgated, and has set everybody using bio- logical language. So too Comte did not think of justifying his favourite virtue of altruism by his favourite science of biology; yet that also has now been tried ; and if the views for which Drummond is champion hold their ground, that also will have been accomplished. One can only repeat once more that it is extraordinary to find a Christian thinker such as Drummond casting in his lot so unreservedly with the programme of naturalistic science. It is from Darwin, however, that the new discussion takes its departure. Its divergence from Darwinism 1 Ascent of Man, p. 57. CHAP, xv REACTION FROM DARWINISM : DRUMMOND 1 59 is, in its own opinion, its most important feature. Let us look then for a moment at the peculiarities of Darwinism. All living species have been marked off from each other, and given a standing ground in nature, by the working of natural selection upon minute and apparently casual variations. The means of selection has been the ceaseless process of struggle for existence. At a certain point in this evolutionary process we have foreshadowings of morality when gregariousness appears, and when social sympathies begin to claim a place in animal life. Such limitation of the struggle for existence marks the dawn of morality. Henceforth sociality has only to develop its latent powers, and to call in the strong help of intelligence, and we have morality full blown. How- ever, the struggle for existence is not terminated; it is only limited or modified. Competition does not go on within the social group ; " dog does not bite dog ; " but the groups still compete with each other. Moral- ity and immorality are both of them natural products. Evolution yields them both ; they are both with us to this day in the strangest blending. Darwin, being neither philosopher, nor moralist, but a student of facts and a seeker of natural laws, was content to publish his views of origin and process without in- quiring very deeply into the probable consequences of such views in their bearing upon morality. The first objection taken was by Miss Cobbe, speak- ing as an intuitionalist. She complained that moral- ity had no more sacredness, no more binding force, if it were true that conscience was a simple remainder of brute tendencies, useful to the species, but having no ideal sanction. That objection we have ventured 160 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in to overrule. Provided only a sufficiently deep view of intelligence or reason be held, — provided we see clearly that reason transforms, perfects, makes new, what it seems to inherit from brute nature, — we need not be afraid for morality though it should universally be taught that morality came into being by slow and gradual fashioning of brute impulse. A somewhat different objection is in the view of Huxley and Drummond, — not the origin of con- science, not the inheritance of moral instinct from brutes, but the swamping (as it were) of moral instinct in the great current of cosmic process, regarded as a struggle for existence. If all nature struggles blindly and selfishly, what should man be but a " strugforli- feur " like the villain in Daudet's novel ? If reason, so we may interpret the difficulty in the light of Mr. Ben- jamin Kidd's work, the destined goal of our present study — if reason teaches man that the whole ani- mated cosmos has been and is controlled by a strug- gle for existence, and by that struggle has been pushed onward and upward, what can man do but reverently bow down before blind selfishness, and practise it in his own life ? Mr. Huxley, a man of science among the moralists, a Saul among the prophets, advancing boldly like Athanasius contra mtmdum, preached the absolute opposition of human morality to cosmic process, and called on his fellow- men to be moral in spite of the nature of things, the cruel, selfish, pain-dealing nature of things, from which we of the human race have arisen. Mr. Drummond and others agree with Huxley and the " strugforlifeur " as to the effect of Darwin's views. But they argue that Darwin's views are one- CHAP, xv REACTION FROM DARWINISM: DRUMMOND l6l sided. They ask us to define nature more exactly, And they fall back upon biology and its categories in making their new survey of the cosmic process. Biology, they tell us, has two main functions, nutri- tion and reproduction. There is indeed a third bio- logical function, co-relation ; but no account is taken of it, in order "to avoid confusing the immediate issue " ; 1 surely a rather airy fashion of dealing with the authority of science ! It is indeed hard to see how and where the omitted function is ever to gain a hearing for itself in the new ethic, based upon the true biology. For the two functions already in evi- dence seem between them to cover the whole ground. " Nutrition" and "reproduction," the "hunger " and " love " of Schiller's witty stanza, claim the whole of life as theirs in joint tenure. The struggle for exist- ence belongs to the first function; it is a struggle for nutrition ; reproduction, with its " other-regard," manifests itself in struggle for the life of others. The male sex stands for the first ; the female sex for the second. Out of the one arises egoism ; out of the other altruism. In their lowest germs these two physiological forces are held to have in themselves and to make manifest the prophecy of their final moral result. Even in reproduction by fission, when a low organism overtaxed by the claims of nutrition upon its existing surface splits in two and becomes two organisms, — even there Drummond thought he could see the Divine law of sacrifice worked into the very fabric of the animal world. But without press- ing such doubtful points we find him urging that sociality and self-sacrifice grow more and more mani- 1 Ascent of Man, p. 17. M 1 62 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m fest as evolution makes farther and farther advances, a plain revelation (he thinks) that morality, the per- fecting of " altruism," is the goal of the entire cosmic process. There are two points of special interest in Drum- mond's statement of evolution. We may dwell shortly upon both. Even if the first does not directly elucidate the alleged new conception of the evolution- ary process, it is important in connection with views that have still to be considered. The point in question is styled by Drummond " the arrest of the body." It seems to follow upon a contri- bution of Dr. A. R. Wallace's, which is very highly praised by Mr. Fiske. In answer to the question, How was natural selection able to differentiate the rational species of mankind from the brute tribes ? or Why did not reason die out as soon or as often as it emerged ? Dr. Wallace replied that reason was pre- served or was selected as soon as it became sufficient in amount to constitute a greater advantage in the struggle than any physical superiority. Upon this a previous question may arise. How was reason, hith- erto unfavoured by the selecting agency, able to leap to that point of magnitude and importance ? That is a difficulty which besets the doctrine of natural selection all along the line, unless the admission is made that variation may proceed per salttim. How- ever, in regard to the origin of reason, the difficulty is met tant bien que mal by treating reason alternately as identical with animal intelligence, and as some- thing wholly new. When the origin of human reason is made the subject of discussion, it is spoken of as a new and advantageous variety ; when the difficulty CHAP, xv REACTION FROM DARWINISM : DRUMMOND 163 of its quantity or amount is referred to, it is treated as a slight improvement upon those lesser amounts of intelligence which are found among the highest of the lower animals. The muscular ape survived the feeble ape, and the clever ape survived the stupid one. The ape which was muscular but stupid, and the ape which was clever but feeble, ran perhaps a dead heat ; but both of them were distanced a great way by the ape which was at once muscular and clever. At last, however, from one of the clever apes was born one cleverer still, one that deserved to be called rational, to be called human. And hence- forth the future lay with him. He might be healthy or he might be feeble, but his endowment of reason made him more than a match for all the apes, more than a match for everything, unless another human child of the apes was evolved, who had the advantage of being more vigorous than the first, while equally rational. In that case the newcomer must be king ! Of the two endowments, however, — and this is Dr. Wallace's point, — reason is the stronger. As soon as reason has become the thing best worth preserving by natural selection, rational beings survive. As soon as a rational race estab- lishes itself, we may be sure that reason is the most important of all its helps in the struggle for existence. To this contribution of Mr. Wallace's, Drummond adds the remark that the advent of reason involves the arrest of the body. Natural selection, it has been im- plied, is turning its attention to the mind. Drummond asks us to consider how this affects bodily evolution. It will terminate physical or animal progress. Man has no more need of an improved body ; he uses im- 164 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART HI proved rational methods. In particular he supple- ments his body by the use of tools. But if man adds new resources to the resources of his body, he also counteracts many of its defects, e.g. he counteracts defective eyesight by the use of spectacles. There is a danger here ; for it is implied that natural selection does not kill off defective human types as it kills off defective animal types. We shall even be told by Weismann that, natural selection ceasing to operate, we ought to postulate not merely the arrest of the body, but its retrogression. Man might not retrograde as a whole; body plus reason he might become a more effective creature in civilised times than he was in savage or barbarous ages ; but "what of his body ? Confessedly, its advance has been arrested. Is it not inevitable that it should have receded, as civilisation has been developed by reason ? If we tried to verify this suggestion by a reference to facts, we should prob- ably meet with a good deal of evidence on both sides. Except the few professional athletes, civilised men are poor creatures physically in comparison with the higher savages. Whole faculties have gone amissing, and others have left the merest aborted remnants. Yet the civilised man displays much physical toughness in the ordeal of disease, while the " noble savage " breaks down. Before leaving this point for the present, we ought to refer to its bearing on the question of man's place in nature. Is man the highest possible product of terrestrial evolution ? That is plainly affirmed by Mr. Fiske ; and the same view is supported by Professor Cleland of Glasgow,1 on more specially anatomical 1 As cited by Drummond, Ascent of Man, p. 144. CHAP, xv REACTION FROM DARWINISM: DRUMMOND 165 grounds, viz. that the human skull has been modified absolutely as far as is possible in favour of brain. If the " crowning race " wish to have much larger brains than the Europeans of to-day, they must do without noses, which would be very awkward for them, not merely from aesthetic considerations. The second point of special interest in Drum- mond's statement is the " evolution of a mother." While sex is the region in which morality is supposed to be concentrated, and while the female sex stand for goodness and altruism in contrast to male egoism and badness, Drummond makes it plain that morality first shows itself not in love for the mate, but in love and care for the offspring. That is true for the mother; in course of time it becomes true for the father. Eventually romantic love between the sexes comes as a long-delayed climax. Rather sentimen- tally Drummond points out that even plants are classed scientifically by a reference to the reproduc- tive process; that all the finest foods, milk, fruit, grain, occur in nature for the sake of reproduction, either animal or vegetable ; that the highest animals are named from the function of the highest physical motherhood, mammalia. More noteworthy is the argument, originally Fiske's, that the still higher development of human society, and with it of human morality, is due to the feebleness of infancy. The prolonged helplessness of human infancy kept the family together, and gave depth and constancy to family relationships. What again was the reason for that helplessness of babyhood ? The complexity of the processes gone through by an adult brain in ra- tional life. Animals, even the highest of the lower 1 66 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in animals, have comparatively few lessons to learn. Their nervous system is always repeating the same combinations. These grow stable by habit, and the young creature is early emancipated from the care of its parents. Not so is it with mankind. Here the elaborate education of the nervous system must be a slow process. During its long course pity, tender- ness, love tremble into consciousness ; a mother is a mother indeed ; man is growing human. Such an outline is the theory. What are we to say of it ? Does Drummond mean us to understand, like Hux- ley or like the Socialists, that struggle is purely bad in the ethical region ? Verbally, he denies this. It is "struggle for the life of others," not absence of struggle, which is more and more to prevail till it dominates humanity. Partly this struggle may be explained as carried on against the forces of nature. Must it not also in part be a struggle between group and group, home and home ? The struggle will no doubt be carried on according to the laws of the game, those laws which we know as justice. It will be lighted up and made dignified by sympathy, by love for those within the group, by consideration even for rivals without. That is a very worthy pro- gramme. But does it not involve dropping the old hard false opposition between egoism and altruism, and dropping the somewhat apocryphal biological deduction of these two opposite tendencies ? If struggle is good, is there not an eternal use and fit- ness in a limited amount of egoism ? Or rather must not that which is called egoism, and marked under that name with obloquy, enter, however transformed, CHAP. Xv REACTION FROM DARWINISM: DRUMMOND 1 6? into the final moral constitution, and the highest human type ? Again we ask, can the male element be purely bad ? And when we come on to the " evolution of a father," we find qualifications introduced. Rather to his own surprise, Drummond has to admit that the alleged feminine soul of goodness is not the only moral type. Authority has a place as well as tender- ness ; justice, or righteousness, Huxley's favourite virtue, is a specially masculine addition to the sym- pathetic virtues. Good again ; but again tending to discredit Drummond's Comtist phraseology and his quasi-biological deduction of righteousness and of sin. Another objection has been brought forward by Mr. B. Kidd. Drummond is said to confuse sociality and family affection, whereas they are distinct things. This seems of small importance. Probably the two things ought to be distinguished. Yet they co-operate ; and, as Drummond has observed, the family is the strongest socialising influence. We touch on a rather more serious point when we inquire whether " struggle for the life of others " is or is not a factor in physical progress. Once, but (I think) only once, Drummond deals with this ques- tion, and gives an affirmative answer, in so far as this, that the best mothers will rear the strongest and most successful offspring. Usually, however, morality or " altruism " is spoken of not as a cause or factor in evolution, but as a feature or result of the evolution- ary process. The retort is almost inevitable from the side of pure or ultra-Darwinism, that natural selection by struggle is the whole fact, struggle for the life 1 68 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m of others only a part of that fact, signifying struggle of group against group, yet assuredly signifying, still and always, struggle. If it be true that ultimately the whole race is " a moral organism," that " we are mem- bers one of another," that the highest and most advanced need the welfare of the most backward, that fact is a spiritual truth. We must not look to find it in nature ; we must not localise it in part of nature, and call this the moral part in contrast to the remainder, which is immoral or wicked. Nature is the presup- position of reason and morality, but reason and moral- ity work up the whole of nature's raw material, not the half merely. As against Huxley, Drummond seems to have been right. As against Darwin, he did not formulate any scientific difference. The same facts are in the view of both — the same facts differently stated and emphasised. To make a decisive advance, Drum- mond needed a more adequate philosophical school- ing. He intended to vindicate all nature for God. Constantly he seems to be vindicating only a section, though perhaps a growing section. That position is of no possible interest to Christian theism. CHAPTER XVI REITERATION OF DARWINISM: ELIMINATION MADE AB- SOLUTE— MR. A. SUTHERLAND A strong book with some weaknesses — Works out the origin of moral feeling by natural selection — Restates Drummond-like position as Darwinian (?) — And exemplifies " arrival " of forms — Biology ; fitness to survive — And to breed and rear — Quantity first relied on — Then quality — This develops sympathy — Which becomes serviceable — Anthropology ; everything depends on the ap- proaches to monogamy — Sociology ; progress is by elimination of the inferior — Even when it seems to find more rapid means — (Yet he allows some progress by imitation !) — History ; retrogres- sion is possible ! — For he hates all militarism — On the whole he does not believe in history — Or in reason — Ethics ; Has dealt only with one-half of goodness ! — Egoism must balance sympathy ! — Balance will grow automatic ! — Criticism ; no right to call sympathy moral, if only half of morality — Nature does not select one quality at a time ! — Selection said to have worked — Not true natural selection though — Why is goodness not automatic already? — Do beauty and goodness exist, or do they not ? — " Yes and no ! " MR. SUTHERLAND'S two handsome volumes are among the most recent, and certainly not the least important, contributions to the biological study of morals. They are interesting in many ways. As a gift from Australia to older lands they deserve a courteous welcome. As the outcome — so we learn from the preface — of eleven years of labour they deserve our respect and almost our reverence. They cover a very wide field, including biology, anthro- 169 I/O FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in pology, history, philosophy. In the first Mr. Suther- land gives many results of his own observation, and so far as a non-expert can judge, he seems admir- ably equipped both as observer and as summariser for speaking on questions of biology. The same might be said regarding anthropology. In history Mr. Sutherland does not profess to be an original scholar, but he quotes to good purpose, and general- ises strikingly. Yet why does a student of Robert- son Smith express himself as if he had never heard of Old Testament criticism ? Why should he speak as if the character or conduct of King Solomon threw any possible light upon the Book of Prov- erbs ? No doubt the Old Testament references are of trifling amount ; but when an author is dependent (necessarily) on a great amount of borrowed ma- terial, one cannot but judge of his quotations from regions beyond one's knowledge by what one sees of his procedure in regions where one is able, so far, to control his method and test his judgment. In philosophy, finally, Mr. Sutherland is well read, but is hardly master of his materials. A writer who supposes that Kant's " moral law " meant the statute law or criminal code, puts himself out of court. And, for our part, we must dissent in the gravest possible way from his philosophical principles. Mr. Sutherland is chiefly interesting to us from the unflinching way in which he carries out the appeal to natural selection, or, as he very tellingly words it, to the working of " elimination," l in one 1 Yet it is questionable whether Mr. Sutherland's elimination is the same process throughout as Darwin's, i.e. whether his natural selec- tion in morals, etc., is true natural selection. CHAP, xvi REITERATION OF DARWINISM 171 region after another. He conducts a valuable ex- periment in seeking to use this one conception as a key to all the mysteries of progress. Mr. Suther- land modestly tells us that he has done little more than expand Darwin's chapter in the Descent of Man. Yet Darwin was concerned with morals only in an incidental fashion. Morality furnished a pos- sible objection to the opinion that man is descended from brute races. Darwin rebutted the objection by showing the affinities between human morality and animal sociality. He did not trace out in de- tail the derivation of the one from the other by the working of natural selection ; and this Mr. Suther- land does, or seeks to do. The appeal is steadily made to natural selection, and natural selection alone. Use-inheritance is "a matter under discus- sion, and on the whole improbable." l Reason is in no sense conceived as modifying the workings of selection which we see in nature. A second feature of special interest in Mr. Suther- land's book is his ingenious restatement of views very like Henry Drummond's in the Ascent of Man, and his restatement of them as the legitimate outcome of the Darwinian tradition.2 To at least one reader Mr. Sutherland's account of the animal anticipations of morality has made the point of view intelligible and impressive as it never was before. One cannot doubt that there is a rehearsal of the whole drama of morals in races lower than man. And one learns from Mr. Sutherland how sympathy, which he treats as the 1 ii. p. 89. 2 Yet this is rather a transformed Darwinism. It gives a more moral view of the animal world (not of the human !). FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m primary form of morality, was actually a factor in securing further progress. Yet a third reason for valuing Mr. Sutherland's book lies in the instances it points out of progress coming to its limit in certain directions, and so terminating. We must now try to describe briefly the leading thoughts of this full and interesting discussion with its admirable wealth of examples. We begin with biology. The first of all necessities is that emphasised by Darwin's doctrine, that the individual organisms should be fit or fittest to survive in the endless strug- gle of life. This postulate, however, does not carry us very far. The individual may survive, but the race will not survive or preponderate unless the vic- torious adult organism is able to bequeath its position to offspring, and thus to reproduce its great qualities — the congenital, if not the acquired qualities — in a subsequent generation. Of course the con- verse is equally true. There can be no transmission of qualities unless there is first, and for a time, per- sonal survival! Therefore, Darwin's postulate may occupy the first place in our list of requisites. But the course of discussion has made the position clearer. It is not individual organism that competes against individual, but stock against stock. The prize of survival goes not simply to individual strength, but to individual strength//^ an abundant healthy offspring. Now there are two ways in which nature has secured, and does secure, the maintenance of species. One is the method of quantity, the other of quality. CHAP, xvi REITERATION OF DARWINISM 173 In the lower forms of life, and in some which are pretty high, fecundity is almost inconceivably great. But the superior method is that of quality. Fewer of the offspring perish at an immature stage, for they are better guarded and better developed either before birth or while still under parental care. The methods are alternatives. As quality rises, quantity recedes. As care for offspring increases, the number of off- spring steadily diminishes ; 1 but every species pretty well holds its own on a net balance. One important side development of the method of quality is the method of the egg, the nest, and the incubating parent; but the crowning method is that of infant helplessness and maternal or parental self-sacrifice, best exemplified in human kind. We see therefore that the higher races are evolved on a principle of family life and family affection. But in this close intercourse of the home or the nest sympathy is born, and sympathy naturally extends itself to other members of the species. Here then we are on the very brink of morality itself. Indeed, we might say that the secret of the evolution of morals is placed by Mr. Sutherland just here. Na- ture, in the case of the higher tribes, required for survival that there should be a strong " perihestic " sympathy, and this sympathy could not be hindered from overflowing into " aphestic " 2 relations. Moral- 1 Does this not point to a variation which is not random ? Are we really to suppose that, in the beginning, animal races produced families of all sizes, indiscriminately, and tended them with all possible degrees of care, until those with unsuitable proportions died off ? 2 Mr. Sutherland's terms, coined by him for human morals, where no doubt they are more fully legitimate. 1/4 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in ity was, so far, a kind of by-product in evolution, though an inevitable by-product. Family sympathy was a necessary cause of predominance in those races which had substituted quality for quantity, care or development of offspring for mere fecundity ; but in the first instance germinal morality, or the wider sympathy, was a symptom rather than a condition of progress. Only, however, in the first instance ; for as animal life drew nearer and nearer the confines of morality, ' and even before it had grown rational, gregariousness or sociality became serviceable.1 The more grega- rious were selected, the less social were eliminated. Here then we have Drummondism brought into relation with natural selection, and exhibited as a subsection in the Darwinian theory. In anthropology Mr. Sutherland is inclined through- out to emphasise the importance of monogamy, and of the poorest, most imperfect approaches to it — never conceding much sway to polygamy, and not attaching importance to those strange phases of social development studied, e.g., in connection with totemism. In other words, Mr. Sutherland — like Mr. Herbert Spencer, though in different form — holds that there were no very complex processes involved in making man so social as he is. It is natural that such views should be advanced by one who puts the centre of moral development in the family, and who believes that all development — moral development, infra-moral development, de- 1 Or so it is argued. The shoal darted away when one fish saw danger ; yes, but did not the shoal become a mark for dangers which solitary individuals might have escaped ? CHAP, xvi REITERATION OF DARWINISM 175 velopment of morals out of the non-moral — is due to natural selection. Mr. Sutherland's views are supported by much evidence as to the character of contemporary savage life. But, if other reports can be trusted, there are features both of the present and of the past which deserve more prominence than they receive with Mr. Sutherland. In general sociological theory Mr. Sutherland is strikingly loyal to his doctrine of elimination. Hu- man or moral progress is due to elimination, not by means of wholesale massacre, but through the grad- ual and unnoticed working of natural law. Criminals as a class leave but few children ; necessarily there- fore, in a generation or two, criminal stocks die out1 — or, shall we say, tend to die out? The vicious and grossly self-indulgent produce or rear few chil- dren; they also die out. Even the coarse and vio- lent tend to kill each other off. "They that take the sword perish with the sword." The meek in- herit the earth by the simple process of "lyin' low and say in' nuffin'," like Brer Fox, or like the Babes in the Wood, while the ruffians dispose of one an- other. All this is vastly well so far as it is true ; but the violent, at any rate, have no special taste for singling out their violent rivals; they are quite as ready to murder, outrage, or plunder the most sym- pathetic and inoffensive of their neighbours. Let us observe however the full force of the posi- tion. This method of elimination is regarded as the 1 What about the Jukes family ? And again, if a criminal popula- tion is generated afresh by society at each stage, have we advanced by the elimination of previous criminals ? 176 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in method of moral progress. It is so certain and so telling that all others may safely be neglected. When Christianity was accepted by the Teutonic barbarians it did not in the least pull them up to its higher moral level. Slowly, in the course of some thousand years or so, the incapable were weeded out and the general level was raised. Those sinners wan- dered in the wilderness for very nearly forty genera- tions till the whole stock died out in detail. This is a doctrine of the most unbounded materialism. It regards man as fatally determined by his antecedents. Free will is a dream, conversion or real repentance an impossibility. Yes, and that is all implied in the attempt to run natural selection right through — to make elimination the only method of moral progress. At one point Mr. Sutherland seems inconsistent with himself. In one passage he almost bursts the shackles of naturalism. He speaks of imitation as a cause of progress — like Bagehot, or like Professor Baldwin. But, so far as imitation acts, elimination is unnecessary. If example can be copied, there is a short cut to progress on the part of the inferior but teachable multitude. In nature imitation plays a very limited part. One species cannot borrow the good habits of another. If it could, you would have transformations ready made without the cumbrous machinery of elimination. And if imitation does work in human history, then, so far as it works, it supersedes natural selection. We may make a separate heading for Mr. Suther- land's conception of history in detail. The method of elimination being always steadily and triumphantly CHAP, xvi REITERATION OF DARWINISM 177 at work, we seem to have before us a programme of the boldest evolutionary optimism. All must be for the best in this best of all possible universes. Prog- ress, it would seem, cannot fail or be checked. That, we think, ought to have been Mr. Sutherland's doc- trine, given his premises. Yet it turns out that he believes the clock went back precisely one thousand years when the barbarians overran the Roman em- pire. It took the barbarians precisely that time — Christianity and all — to reach the social and moral level of ancient Rome (! !) — and then progress re- commenced. Now, what does this singular view mean ? Perhaps for one thing it means that Mr. Sutherland — like Mr. Spencer, yet not altogether like him; unlike Bagehot — has no sense of the moral worth of war, under whatever circumstances waged. It means that the masculine ideal, in spite of some isolated references to it, is left out of the reckoning, while the feminine ideal of sympathy is given a place of absolute predominance and authority. In a world wholly governed by natural selection, soft- ness surely ought to be ranked as a deadly sin. The Roman empire had grown too soft to fight. It was not therefore advanced, but retrograde, and unfit to survive. The barbarians may have been one thou- sand years behind, tried by certain tests ; but, in the light of the most practical of all tests, they were not behind, but before. Of course Mr. Sutherland's ultimate definition of "morality," as we shall find, makes it only one constituent of human well-being. Surely a very unfortunate abuse of terminology in a moral treatise ! Another qualification of Mr. Sutherland's views — 1/8 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m by common sense — slips out when he speaks of Howard the philanthropist1 as moving his age. Now, this is curious. Christianity had no chance with the Teutonic peoples till natural selection killed off the heathen and barbarous majority; John How- ard, without waiting for natural selection to make "Howards of us all," was able to "move the hearts" of his fellow-countrymen. And yet Howard, with all his qualities, was surely not comparable to the founder of the Christian faith ? The one had his milieu ready made; the other had to create his milieu; but was His greatness not tolerant of that extra burden ? Or put it at the lowest : if personal influence is capable of doing anything, is there not a factor in moral progress to be reckoned with, independently of natu- ral selection ? On the whole, however, we might almost say that Mr. Sutherland does not believe in any such thing as history, or the throbbing and thrilling of the social organism to one great life. In history the public mind "moveth altogether if it move at all"; what- ever lies below consciousness, there is a conscious life, and the conscious service of common ideals. But Mr. Sutherland will have it that nothing ever happens, except the interminable weeding of the hu- man garden. The bad die out ; the good have only to stand still, and they, or their stock, will be carried on by forces outside of them to a far distant triumph. We are in no sense members one of another. We are not so much men as things — things exactly like other things — or exceptional only in this, that we can find out in what direction we are tending, while we 1 i. p. 420, CHAP, xvi REITERATION OF DARWINISM 179 are utterly incapable of modifying that direction or of altering the pace. Along with Mr. Sutherland's doctrine of history we may take his doctrine of reason, which resembles the other doctrine closely. There is no such thing as reason. Applying natural selection to every pro- cess, from the life of the amoeba to that of the saint, Mr. Sutherland scarcely has room for reason in his system. And therefore he shows us nature selecting the fittest emotions in the form of so many physio- logical processes — consciousness being a mere blind alley ; it came no one can say how or why ; it leads nowhere. The appropriate emotions are organic to our race, in total independence of the accident of rea- son or consciousness. They might last if it lapsed ; they are untouched and unaffected by it. It is a practical nullity, and ought not to have troubled our theories by existing at all.1 Passing on to morals, we meet with the great sur- prise of the book. By " moral instinct " Mr. Suther- land means sympathy. There is, he says, no instinct which tells us what is right and what is wrong ; moral opinion could not vary as it does if instinct were con- 1 Mr. Sutherland ascribes emotions to a bodily source, and remarks that Professor William James has reached similar views. One observes, however, that Professor Lloyd Morgan speaks of the " almost paradoxi- cal emphasis of Mr. James's views," and of " making them somewhat less repugnant to common sense " by confining them to the first rise of emotion, in contrast to subsequent emotions qualified by " association." — Habit and Instinct, p. 190. Dr. S. H. Mellone {Studies in Philo- sophical Criticism and Construction, p. 249) states that Professor Dewey has maintained the paradox with more determination than Professor James, ISO FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in trolling it. There is, however, a sympathetic instinct • — the creation of natural selection. And that in- stinct tells us one of the conditions of right conduct ; another of the conditions, however, is dictated by the egoistic instinct. Right action is a resultant of these forces, or a compromise between them. Here, then, our great Darwinian in morals suddenly becomes a Spencerian in morals. And he goes all the way with Mr. Spencer. He looks forward to an age of per- fected balance, when good conduct will be automatic ; when there will presumably be a moral instinct ! Natural selection, steadily killing off the inferior types, will at last produce that " crowning race." Now, is this fair ? Truly, it is easy to show that morality is an outgrowth of sympathy if you define what is " moral " as equivalent to what is sympa- thetic ! All the time we are reading Mr. Suther- land's record of moral evolution we suppose that we are being shown the gradual origin of real central goodness, — of that spirit which embodies itself in right conduct, and does so willingly. Suddenly we learn that our impression was wrong ; that was not what was being shown ; we were looking on at the production of one constituent of goodness, but the other constituent, which is no less important, is quite a different thing ! Then were the morally advanced Romans, who succumbed before the barbarian in- roads, not really better men, but just more sympa- thetic ? The whole book had need to be rewritten. Mr. Sutherland must not talk of morality if he has in view only one-half of its conditions. Language has its rights, and the truths embodied in language must not be flouted, or they will take their revenge. CHAP, xvi REITERATION OF DARWINISM l8l Moreover, it seems very doubtful whether Mr. Sutherland is entitled to assume that natural selec- tion has developed sympathy, but has developed it in uncertain measure, so that it may be perhaps too much in amount, perhaps too little. Natural selec- tion has taught the lower and the higher animals exactly how many offspring to produce. Why has it not taught me exactly how much sympathy I am to feel ? Why has it developed a force uncertain in amount and working ? Unless because, after all, spirit is different from nature; because it is incon- ceivable that natural selection, and natural selection alone, has "out of darkness" stretched forth "the hands that reach through nature, moulding men." Again, let us note that two qualities have been selected — two seemingly if not really opposite quali- ties— egoism and altruism.1 How may this be? Nature has really been selecting men, not qualities, men (or societies of men) who are the sum of all their qualities. Nature is regarded as a hanging judge. Every crime in her calendar is a capital offence. If nature is not satisfied with you, "off with his head," she cries; and forthwith you are thrust out. Nature has not been selecting one quality at a time ; she has been selecting aggregate fitness. It is lawful to study the process one quality at a time, if you like. But you must keep in mind that that is your own "abstraction." The only question with nature has been, first and last, who is in the aggre- gate fittest to survive ? Fitness has been selected, not quality A tending to fitness, nor quality B tend- ing to fitness, but A + B+ . . . M. And again, from 1 Mr. Sutherland thinks the latter word stilted, and avoids it. 1 82 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m this rather different point of view, we are struck with the anomalousness of the fact that natural selection, if it has really been at work, has not already produced an automatic balance between egoism and altruism, or has not done so in the past if it is going to do so in the future. There might indeed be an explanation, if sym- pathy in its wider range outside the family were only (what Mr. Sutherland holds it was primarily) a by- product in evolution. In that case sympathy ought to be a casual and fluctuating factor in human nature.1 But Mr. Sutherland carefully rules out that view. Sympathy has been in the main a condition of suc- cess, and has been selected as such through untold ages. Is not Darwinism, at least apart from statis- tical tables,2 a dangerously plastic method ? Any- thing and everything may be conceived as a quality tending in some way and to an undefined degree towards predominance. Anything and everything may be ticketed, " First prize, for fitness to survive." The formula of Darwinism Is twice too big, And therefore needs must fit. Indeed, one observes that, in spite of his Darwinian phraseology, Mr. Sutherland is not thinking of natural selection per se as an evolutionary force, but of natural 1 Compare Mr. A. J. Balfour's remarks upon the aesthetic sense (Foundations of Belief, Book IV.), based on the assumption of evolu- tion by natural selection. 2 Demanded by Mr. Karl Pearson in The Chances of Death, etc. — Dr. Pearson, one notes, is a Professor of Applied Mathematics. — His suggestion deserves consideration. CHAP, xvi REITERATION OF DARWINISM 183 selection modified by the presence of animal sympathy. This seems a true account of the facts of nature, but it is a miserably inadequate account of the facts of human society ; and unfortunately Mr. Sutherland ad- mits no morality among men beyond the rudimentary morality which he finds in the brute world. Elimination must do everything for us ; it cannot ! And whatever elimination does for human advance it is precisely that elimination which is least like the Darwinian that sur- vives the advent of reason. If the child of vicious or criminal or heartless parents is neglected and dies, while the child of honest, pure, and affectionate parents survives, there is no struggle. The better care paid to the second child is not the cause why the first succumbs. If the ill-cared-for child were the only child in the world, it must still die of neglect. " Elimination " here is not a case of selection after struggle ; it is nature's own protest against vice and exuberant selfishness. But let us pursue the subject further. Does Mr. Sutherland habitually place himself outside of morality, and view it with scientific coolness, as one quality tending towards success ? Or does he write from the inside, with a glow of admiration for " the true, the just"? Very often he does the latter. It would be altogether to misrepresent Mr. Sutherland if we did not confess that he writes like a good man and a lover of goodness. But in his final attitude he seeks to com- bine both views. Goodness is authoritative for us ; we are bound to be loyal to it ; we must speak and think and feel as if goodness were something objective and absolute, cosmical, divine ; and yet reason forces us to be agnostics. Goodness is nothing but one of 1 84 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART nt the conditions of race efficiency and race survival. Beauty is nothing in itself ; and the sense of beauty is mere habituation to environment, whether from in- herited experience (Lamarck, Spencer, also Darwin) or from the slower but not less sure (Darwinian) pro- cess of elimination. We must steadily occupy a posi- tion on both sides of the hedge. Mr. Sutherland is determined to warm his hands, as long as he lives, at a painted fire. He knows it is painted ; you shall not throw dust in his eyes ! He is determined to keep on warming himself ; how dare you forbid him ? We at least have no wish to do so. We would rather hope that some day he may discover the glorious truth, that what warms him is not paint, but God's own sunshine. CHAPTER XVII THE METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION I. Chance in relation to purpose, as accident — As absence of design — In relation to law ; as blind law — As blind combination of laws — Compare with the last the scientific or mechanical view of the world ; a number of separate substances ruled by a number of independent laws — Good enough for science, not for philos- ophy— Darwin ought not to assume things as really discon- nected, merely because he has not needed to investigate their connection — As if organism and environment were accidentally brought together — Or as if organism and organism were mere rivals — (They are rivals !) — Or as if force and force were dis- connected? II. Darwin treats variation as casual, i.e. as a thing with no bearing in itself on the purpose of the species — His theory allows this assumption — But does not prove it — We all habitually under- stand the theory in that sense, e.g. in contrasting natural selec- tion with use-inheritance — On the fact, evidence is wanted — Conceivably variation may choose very irregularly between many fixed possibilities — This seems to point back to disconnected laws, as in last section III. Even on Darwin's own view he is hardly entitled to call the process of evolution natural selection — Aggregate range of possible variation is fixed by the nature of the material — Two agencies must be taken together — Of the two the varying organism, not the blindly selecting environment, seems the better to account for rise of new qualities — Summary of I., II., III. IV. Kinds of natural selection, A, B, and C — B exists ! — If organic evolution is a fact, C exists ! — Accelerating any other evolution- ary force that may exist, and of course involving B — If A is found alongside of C, A must have a separate field where C can- not enter, else inconsiderable — Natural selection (C) lasts as long as nature is nature — Even along with (the more rapid 185 1 86 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in force of) animal intelligence — True reason checks it — Does natural selection ever work by itself (A) ? — Higher animals with fewer births evolve as quickly as lower ; has a new force arisen ? or was natural selection never the leading force ? — [Can we regard intelligence as the new evolving force ? Dr. Mellone assumes its operation everywhere !] V. Can natural selection apply to men? — Biologically — Struggle with beasts is over — Famine (A) is rare, and of doubtful ten- dency — Pestilence (C) does harm — Vice (B) — Crime (B) — War (selects the wrong way) — Religious celibacy (*£.) — Sum- mary— Sociologically — Mr. Kidd's insistence on struggle is really biological ; is unproved; is not an insistence on natural selection — Ethically — Mr. Alexander's competition of "Ideals " is exaggerated — And itself implies reason and sympathy — Mr. Sutherland's elimination of evil doers ignores positive causes of moral progress — Exemplified typically in Jesus Christ VI. If natural selection does not operate where reason and conscience exist, it yet may originate them in the loose and incorrect sense in which natural selection is said to originate things ! — If reason, etc., were, as most suppose, evolved and selected — How selected? — Have adjacent races died out? VII. Other idealist views — Professor Ritchie praises natural selection more fully, in vague terms and in some passages — Mr. Sande- man rejects it, because he believes in the Ideological perfection of every organism — But is it possible to get over the impression produced by rudimentary organs? — It is enough if the whole of nature \sgood, and its parts relatively Jit — Dr. Stirling believes the casual variation which makes an individual can never make a type — Is it certain that every individual is born differentiated? — Or that any differences are incapable of growing by cumula- tion into a type ? — Possible value of the hypothesis of natural selection, even if a fiction IT was no part of the plan of this book to undertake a direct criticism of theories of evolution upon their merits, whether from the point of view of biology or of philosophy, of science or of metaphysics. If we now find it necessary to undertake an estimate of the value of Darwinism, we do so not merely because of the outstanding importance of that theory, but because CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 187 in summing up results, we are led to insist on a dis- tinction. While we admit, and even (so far as we have any right to speak) defend, the theory of natural selection in biology, we affirm that it cannot be ap- plied in sociology or morals. Such a view seems to need justification. It can only be supported by a review, however hurried and imperfect, of the merits of Darwinism. The question may perhaps best be approached by a discussion of the element of chance contained, or said to be contained, in the Darwinian theory. Perhaps some minds love Darwinism, because it appeals to chance ; others undoubtedly distrust and despise it for that reason. What is chance ? Does Darwinism assert chance, and, if so, in what sense ? How far is it warranted in doing so ? First and most simply, chance is the opposite of purpose. It implies a failure of purpose where the presence of purpose and its successful realisation were expected. A train is meant to carry me safely to my journey's end- — that is purpose. Instead of doing so it runs off the rails ; the natural forces set to work were imperfectly known or imperfectly controlled. That is accident, not purpose. Neither the passen- gers nor the company's servants designed that result. When a young rough puts a stone upon the track, and wrecks a train, that is not " accident," though by a natural extension of the term we may call it so. That is not chance, but wicked purpose. It is crime. Darwinism does not exactly assert chance in this sense, although it may seem to do so. Apparently 1 88 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in Darwin himself believed that he had destroyed the evidence in support of purpose or design in nature. J. S. Mill, too, looking at the new doctrine, thought that, if it were established, it would substitute chance for design. The evidence for the latter would go to pieces on the " plurality of causes." But even if Darwinism should be held to destroy teleology, such a view involves using the word " chance " in a sense markedly different from that in which we have denned it above. Chance or "accident" in human life means partial failure of purpose through man's weakness or ignorance — partial failure standing out in sharp relief against a background of habitual success. He aimed, as he always does, but he missed the mark this time. That is what we mean (so far) when we say "the disaster was due to chance;" "he had a dreadful accident yesterday. " There is no full parallel between this and Darwin's wholesale denial of teleol- ogy in nature. There was no one to take aim, hints Darwin. Moreover, it is not enough to deny teleology. It is necessary, if you are to carry weight, that you give a plausible explanation of the fact that nature mimics purpose. Darwin has given such an explanation. What part does chance play in it? If we cannot fully interpret chance by a reference to telic purpose, we must bring it into relation with efficient causation — or causal law, as we ordinarily phrase it ; efficient cause, or that scientific conception of cause which stands nearer to efficiency than to any other of Aristotle's " causes," having well-nigh monopolised the name of cause in the minds of modern men. CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 189 The assertion of chance will now imply either (i) mere blind causal law, in opposition to purpose, or else (2) mere blind coincidence of several uncon- nected laws or forces. The phrase is often used in the first sense in de- nunciation of Materialism. Did mere blind causal law, it is asked, — did the mere law of matter blunder into mind ? This, however, could not be Darwin's sense. He denied purpose; but it was not at all his affair to disparage causal law. Besides, it is not the case that any one cause (not being a mental " First Cause ") can be said to account for living species. " Natural selection," the supposed creator of distinct " species," is a group of many different causal factors, curiously entangled with each other. We are driven then upon the last sense. A chance is a coincidence. Series A and Series B cross each other at one point, and affect each other unexpectedly — it may be grievously. They are distinct things; but they " happen " to have their existence side by side in the same universe ; presently they " happen " to exchange their formation side by side for a hostile formation, front against front, and there is a collision, — it was an accident ! The wind that blew over the rotten tree, the cry that caused the child to run forward, had no connection with each other. But the child " happened " to be just under the tree as it fell, and was crushed — by accident. The champion of ethics must not look askance upon the doctrine of chance in this sense. Chance and choice are very closely connected. Man can neither create nor annul force. He can govern it only by determining where one current shall cross another. I QO FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD TART in No contingency in nature, would imply, No free will in man ! or at least, no power of affecting external nature by his will. Moreover, this form of the doctrine of chance, or something very like it, is involved in the logic of science. We call it mechanism. The " finite " sciences take a mechanical view of the universe. They reduce its processes to a few elementary substances (chemi- cal elements, e.g.), actuated by a few elementary forces. Sometimes, as in Mr. Herbert Spencer, we find more fundamental views of evolution proceeding spontaneously from a homogeneous material unity ; but such views are a dreamy speculation ; they have neither the demonstrativeness nor the definiteness which are the glory of science.1 Science is content to pause — where perhaps it thinks that knowledge itself pauses — at the discovery of distinct separate substances and distinct separate forces. And so to it the universe is a machine — not an organism ; the co-operation of distinct parts explains the cosmos; its unity is not (as in an organism) prior to the dis- tinction of parts from each other. May we take it that, as long as we are thinking in terms of matter, this view is correct ? That such a mechanical view of the universe is the ideal goal of (finite) science ? Speculative thinkers will ask for more. The mind 1 This characterisation may seem to ignore the law of the correlation of forces or transmutation of energy. But how far does that law carry us ? What does it affirm ? Different forces are different manifesta- tions of one force, taking their shape under different given conditions. I do not see that science can simplify beyond that statement. Accord- ingly, the given conditions represent the " ultimate " plurality, with which scientific analysis leaves us. CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION IQI itself may demand some deeper or fuller unity. Are not the different substances in some way calculated or adjusted or related to each other ? Is their co- existence purely casual ? Is the quantity of each (so far as we can speak of quantity in the whole universe — so far as we can treat the universe as finite) purely casual, or is it determined by some obscure law ? These questions lie beyond the range of the special sciences, which carry on their business quite success- fully apart from such researches, finishing their own work upon the crude assumptions of mechanism — a few substances ; arbitrarily given quantities of each ; a few elementary laws. Possibly, as we have said, you cannot reasonably go farther unless you quit the logic of science for philosophy — unless you exchange matter for some frankly idealist conception of reality. Within science, then, there seems to be a doctrine of co-existence closely analogous to what we mean in ordinary speech by chance. It differs in one respect ; " chances " are occasional interferences, while science details the habitual co-operation of law with law. The difference supplies science with one excuse for declining to endorse an appeal to mere " chance " on the part of Darwinism. But the conceptions of scientific mechanism and of chance co-existence are identical at heart. Both take as given several inde- pendent substances and processes, without asserting or believing in any wider law connecting them with each other. There is indeed a different way of escape besides the metaphysical shifting of the point of view. We may address ourselves to old-fashioned teleology. Keeping the idea of hard, repellent, individual things, 1 92 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m we may suppose that a designing and combining force, external to themselves, crushes them together into a unity. But such a philosophy is liable to be charged with dualism. And not without reason; it is quite as mechanical, in its own way, as the logic of science. Here once more two elements, which as the Germans say "belong together," are made to fall asunder. The material elements or forces, and the law of their combination, are assigned to different quarters. Nature has no tendency in itself towards life ; a Deistic God outside of nature forces His thought of life upon alien materials, as the human sculptor forces the design of his brain upon the mar- ble, which was fused in nature's laboratory without any reference to the needs of artist or artizan. Hence also it is clear why a system of idealism, which tries to show that all things are related together, and esr pecially that design and materials belong to each other, becomes suspected of pantheism. There is undoubtedly a pantheistic strain in it. Are we sure that there is not a pantheistic strain in the truth and nature of things ? It is not any form of teleology, but, on the con- trary, the purely and characteristically analytic pro- cedure of science, that we seem to find in Darwin. With him, natural selection is a biological hypothesis. He proposes to account for all the different living species from a few given elements — (i) organisms, multitudinous in number but simple in kind, distinct from each other, hostile, competing for the prize of survival; (2) an environment in which life is possible; (3) heredity ; (4) variability. The first three factors sum up in the result (a) struggle ; and all four fac- CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 193 tors taken together give us the final result (b) selec- tion. The immediate outcome of Darwin's theory as a contribution to science is this, he needs no additional factor. The factors already named suffice (he holds) to account for the further result — many distinct liv- ing species. As a scientific worker, Darwin simply postulates his small array of causes existing casually alongside of each other. The man of science has no need to search more deeply, and Darwin does not do so. But, when natural selection is generalised as a philo- sophical theory, when it is applied to other depart- ments of existence, outside of and above biology, we must raise deeper issues. We must not allow the as- sumption to pass as matter of course, that the " ab- stractions," which are legitimate and necessary in special sciences, are facts, or are determining condi- tions of all human thinking. Because you have skil- fully dissected the world into a few separate limbs or tissues, and can show exactly how they fit together, it does not follow that no subtle " spiritual bond " has eluded your scalpel. Because you can explain your special problem without asking whether organism and environment, organism and organism, force and force, have any necessary relation to each other beyond the bare fact of co-existence, it does not follow that you have demonstrated the unreality of such a relation- ship. You have assumed its non-existence — or rather you have ignored the whole question ; and quite fairly for a special purpose. But you have proved nothing. And the sceptical programme is improbable, perhaps impossible; "mechanism made absolute; chance the only nexus between the ele- ments of nature ! " 194 FROM. COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART ill Such is the view of Darwinism which I suggest. Those who entirely reject natural selection, even as a biological hypothesis, may insist with a good deal of force that organic life — that curious half-way house between nature and spirit — or may insist that animal life, so far as psychical, already shares largely the nature of spirit ; that therefore we are guilty of folly in treating it on physical or mechanical lines. If in an organism the whole is prior to the parts, can we explain the genesis of organic species by the co-exist- ence and interaction of [things which we treat as] distinct parts ? The objection is forcible. Does it not amount to saying that a science of biology is impossible ? That philosophy must annex to its own department all treatment of the problems of life ? I think such a view extreme. Let us see how the doctrine of chance or of mechanism works out in sundry particulars of the Darwinian hypothesis. Organism and Environment. — Darwin assumes elementary living forms (else he has nothing to make species out of), and plenty of them (else there will be no struggle). He takes them for granted: they have a suitable environment; they live and are able (some of them) to survive. It is not his affair to ask whether organism and environment have any mystic connection. He takes them as given. They are facts — just facts. Yes; but it is a very long step indeed from this point of view to the denial of teleology, to the assertion that organic fitness itself arose through natural selec- tion by the weeding out of unfit forms. The ignoring of the problem of necessary relation between organ- CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 195 ism and environment is one thing, the denial of such relation is quite a different thing, and nothing in scientific Darwinism justifies it. Darwin the biologist has shown us how life may advance, build itself up, differentiate itself; how fit may become fitter. He has not shown us how unfit may tumble into fitness. Among the postulates of his process of biological evolution are numerous fit living forms. Organism and Organism. — These, Darwin tells us, have nothing to do with each other except to struggle against each other. Not all creatures stand directly in relations of struggle. Probably a whale and a robin red breast have no influence on each other's estate. But, when organisms do affect one another, they do so on terms of hostility. Some species prey upon others. In adjacent species, and within the same species, there is (from our point of view, not from theirs ; they have not consciousness to intensify it), there is competition for nourishment. All of them cannot survive times of scarcity or danger. The weak have their chance but get weeded out. This statement ignores (i) animal sociability and mutual help, usually, not always, between creatures of the same species. Competition, it may be argued, is largely a human surmise or interpretation; sociality is a fact, psychical as well as physical, in animal life. (2) It ignores the dependence of animals upon living food of some kind. True, the relation of the eaten to the eater is not one of friendship. Yet it is a highly positive relation. It is not the whole truth about the cosmos of life that its many species and innumerable organisms are inconsistent with each other. The food species does not simply struggle against the pred- 196 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in atory species by flight, mimicry, protective organs, etc. ; it makes such species possible. Having made these deductions from its value, can we accept natural selection by struggle as a (or the) great method of evolution and lever of progress in nature? There is no great presumption, surely, in putting the question ! The evidence in favour, not of organic evolution, but of natural selection as its method, is deductive and hypothetical; the same thing indeed is true of many of our scientific theories. The evidence for natural selection is as follows: (i) Struggle and selection are facts; (2) They will — given time enough — account for quite as much progress, quite as much differentiation, as we see in the cosmos of life; (3) Therefore, by the law of parsimony, they have caused it. All this is only probable evidence, and " the plurality of causes " may undermine it. Accordingly we claim the right of criticising the theory, and asking whether it is antecedently credible. It is thinkable that the evo- lution of life proceeds along lines of struggle ? — Surely that is thinkable. The doctrine merely im- plies that living organisms are parts of nature and are treated as such ; that though the organic and the animal may approach the spiritual, they have not yet reached it. And, by naming one intelligible and thinkable process of evolution in organisms, Darwin has even helped the cause of sound philos- ophy and the cause of faith. When we meet with intelligible processes, we perceive the presence of reason in the world ; and when the Christian per- ceives reason at work, he is more than ever assured that the world he lives in is God's world. CHAP, xvn METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 197 Force and Force. — Symmetry with what has gone before would lead us to head our next paragraph with these words. But it is questionable whether we can fairly charge Darwin with treating the different bio- logical forces involved in natural selection — life, variability, heredity — as mutually independent and merely coincident things. Scientific logic may in- cline students of science to do this, but a wholesome sense of biological realities will keep them in check. Where Darwin is open to question in this re- gion is in his doctrine of variability. Is variation related in any intelligible fashion to heredity ? Or is it purely " casual " ? Perhaps we shall find that Dar- win emphasises the mechanical blending of distinct heredities — that "heredity and heredity" are pitted against each other in his thinking, quite in the spirit of the logic of chance. The question is so important, and at the same time so complex and obscure, that we had better make a fresh heading for it. II We have to ask then whether there is a special appeal to chance by Darwin in his doctrine of variations ? Darwin largely treated these as casual, almost as if uncaused. But it was not, for the moment, his affair to say how variations arose ; he was to show how they worked out. He never thought of assert- ing deliberately that variations are uncaused; his followers explicitly deny and repudiate any such view. 198 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in What Darwin has done is to assume that variations are casual in reference to the purpose of the species ; that the individual variations arising in nature, so long as they are unweeded by struggle, do not di- rectly tend to fitness. In this sense Darwin affirms, or rather implies, chance — chance in contrast with purpose, but yet with a distinct shade of meaning from either of the senses of chance as against pur- pose which we noted above. Not (i) partial failure of purpose is implied, as when men fall into acci- dents. Nor yet (2) entire absence of (proved) purpose, as when Darwinism is said to destroy the teleological argument for the being of God. But (3) partial ab- sence of purpose. While all the other processes of plant or animal life are purposeful, variation moves at random. Darwin we say assumed this. He did so when he called the entire process Natural Selection. If varia- tion itself were (to any extent) purposeful, progress would not depend entirely upon the selecting agency ; but Darwin's nomenclature implies that indirect selec- tion is the only cause of progress. He had invented a theory which would account for evolution even if variations were non-purposeful. It was natural to slip into a habit of speaking as if variations had been proved to be non-purposeful. But that had not been proved. Nothing had been proved about variations. And so long as we are without laws of variation, it is very hard to define the meaning and bearing of Darwinism. For example, the general bearing of use-inheritance is naturally denned thus : it will give the same results with natural selection, only more rapidly. But in CHAP, xvn METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 199 speaking so one assumes, what is habitually assumed, and never proved, that variation is casual, i.e. non- advantageous (in itself and on the average). If it turned out that variation moved even in part along the lines of evolutionary change, then Darwinism or even Hyper-Darwinism might warrant the hope of rapid progress. Hence it is extraordinarily difficult to bring to the test of experiment the questions between the Lamarckians and the Weismann school. One glides into the habit of thinking that it is mainly a question of pace. And yet quick pace, if it were proved, might not be a presumption in favour of Lamarckian use-inheritance. It might only point to a neglected element in Darwinism, to the necessity of regarding variation per se as telic not casual. We do not mean here to affirm that variation must be advantageous, or even that it must proceed along definite lines. We merely claim that such possibili- ties should not be forgotten. The questions are questions of fact, and further evidence is required. Causeless variations are inconceivable things ; in that view, presumably, all will agree. But, just as little as the evolutionist would waste time over a hypothesis which involved surrendering the causal law, so little would others consent to trifle with a great question by framing the hypothesis of variations perversely opposed to the specific type. Still, within limits, we might conceive of " casual " variations, if variability worked along one of several fixed ' possible directions, while the reasons why it chose one track rather than another were highly obscure. Let us take an illustration. Every house of two or more storeys must include a staircase. The stair may 200 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in be straight as a ladder, or it may be spiral, or it may be a series of straight flights with landings, or it may even be attached to the outside of the house like the "bonnie, bonnie outside stairs" at Thrums. The one thing illegitimate is to omit the stairs, as the amateur who draws his own plans is so apt to do. Well then, in variation, the spiral staircase may be beaten into flat sections, or the outside stair may be brought within doors, or vice versa. Variation may be " casual " in this sense, that it is liable to take any one of several directions. Pattern A or B replaces C, — you cannot say why. Variation will not be casual in the sense of omitting what is advantageous or necessary. It will not leave out the staircase. Experience shows that when animal " monstrosi- ties " occur, they are not strictly congenital. They are the result of accident after development had begun. As to the reason why variation goes thus or thus in so irregular a fashion; in a different region one would be inclined to interpret irregularity as meaning the (casual or intermittent) blending of several (dis- tinct) laws, the imposing of several curves one upon another. And so we should be brought back to a " chance " [under obscure temporary conditions ?] blending of distinct influences [parental, ancestral ?]. Tentatively then we would decide that Darwin appeals to chance and that he is right in doing so. He appeals to chance by the assumption that vari- ation is or may be random in its direction, — harmful quite as often as helpful. And — still more tenta- tively — we propose to identify " chance " in this sense with " chance " in a sense already discussed — CHAP, xvn METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 2OI the mechanical addition to each other of separate forces interfering with one another's drift. In the present instance, the forces in question are of the nature of hereditary tendencies. But, while we sug- gest this view tentatively, as good science, we are sure that it cannot be the final truth on the point. The last word upon most topics must be spoken not by science but by philosophy. Ill The phrase Natural Selection. — Thirdly, we have still further to inquire whether, even on Darwin's own view of evolution, the name natural selection is quite a fair description of the evolutionary process. Dar- win the biologist may be right in his facts and causes, and yet Darwin the philosopher may be wrong in the emphasis he throws upon different features in his system, or in the wider suggestions that grow out of his statements of biological doctrine. Now, Darwin's language seems to attribute greater scope to chance than is allowed to it by the deliberate processes of his thinking. The name natural selection seems to imply that progress is due, though negatively and indirectly, to the environment alone. Organisms evolve, it would seem, because of a foreign influence, forcing advance on the reluctant materials. The whole cause of progress lies in the selecting envi- ronment, not in the varying organism ; and selection proceeds blindly by destruction of the unfit. Here again we have the spirit of the doctrine of chance. We see it partly in the assumption that organism and environment have nothing to do with each other, 2O2 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m partly in the assertion that (if not the existence 6f life ; to take the same view on that point involves a further stretch of the spirit of materialism; yet) all advances in life are due to conditions resident in the environment, operating outside and apart from the purposeful processes of the living creature. To say that "natural selection" causes this or that is almost equivalent to saying that " casual co-existence " creates this or that. One is tempted to take up the very opposite position, and assign whatever is new in evolution, even according to Darwin's own analysis, to the varying organism, and not to the selecting environment. " Natural selection " seems a fair enough name for the evolutionary process (as con- ceived by Darwin), so far as that to which it applies can be regarded as one thing evolving continuously throughout the process. Thus life may be said to differentiate itself into new and finer forms "by natural selection." But natural selection can do no more. It cannot " explain " how matter should pass into life, or how animality should evolve rationality. If for any purpose, or from any point of view, we have to emphasise novelty as novel, then it is un- reasonable to speak of the evolutionary process which led to it, even if Darwin's analysis of that process be accepted, by the name of "natural selection." There must have been possibilities in " protoplasm " answer- ing to all the novel results of late evolution. Let the variations come up as they may ; let them point in every direction by turns, quite at random, if you insist upon it ; still, apart from the amount or direction of each individual congenital variation, there must be a total possible range of variations, prescribed by the CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 2O3 material, and at the very most merely elicited by natu- ral selection. Of the two then, life, not environment, the living creature itself, and not the non-living conditions round about it, explains the acquisi- tion of new qualities and the development of fresh specific types. Of the two, Darwin has emphasised the wrong one, and has isolated it by assuming its merely casual relation to the other. So we might speak, in one-sided opposition to Darwin's graver one-sidedness. But the truly reasonable view to hold is that both together — varying organism and selecting environment — and both as elements in one orderly process, lead to evolution. We do not blame Darwin for speaking in contrac- tions. By the necessity of the case human language is elliptical. The one exception proving the rule is furnished by the lawyers. They omit nothing ; they recite everything in detail over and over again ; and they are the awful example of verbosity, the drunken helots of human speech. But elliptical nomencla- ture, however necessary, is full of dangers. If I were driving pigs to market I might reasonably (though elliptically) say that they got there because I headed them off at all the wrong roads which we had to pass. Yet it would be perilous to affirm that " heading off " was the one cause why they got to market. They got there because they were quad- rupeds, and disliked being hit. (I waive, as possibly not directly relevant, the further consideration that there was some one to drive them.) Yet our modern evolutionists talk as if barricading the wrong roads not only kept pigs from straying, but actually taught them for the first time how to walk. 204 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in When we turn to use-inheritance once more we see that it also may be so developed as to convey the same vicious suggestion. New qualities come from without, not from within ; from the environment, and not from the organism. The environment stamps them on the passive organism, and it (according to the doctrine of use-inheritance) transmits them to offspring. But Mr. Sandeman has forestalled this opinion by a remark of brilliant force and point. Every acquired quality, he observes, is congenital [in its rudiments], and every congenital quality is also acquired [i.e. developed in the course of life]. Of course this is a very strong form of statement, and it seems to forbid all use of the wonted distinction. But presently, having fired off his epigram, and hav- ing bowled over his enemy with it, Mr. Sandeman descends to a less rarefied atmosphere, and admits that the two possibilities may be contrasted as matters of fact and [conceivably, though experiment is diffi- cult here] of evidence. For the truth is that every living creature is more or less plastic in definite direc- tions; and life develops this or that ; so it is a fair question whether or not the offspring resemble the parent as modified in his own development prior to his begetting offspring. But Mr. Sandeman's para- dox serves as a warning. We must not go to use- inheritance for the direct production of new qualities in the organism, miracle fashion, by an alien envi- ronment. In a sense, use-inheritance is a more teleo- logical theory than natural selection ; yet it may be subordinated to the most extremely mechanical phi- losophy, if in " use " environment is held to be active and the organism itself passive. CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 205 Regarding Darwinism and chance then we have decided as follows: — First, Darwinism asserts chance (co-existence) in the same way in which [finite] science ordinarily asserts it, by a mechanical view of the uni- verse ; secondly, Darwinism has also assumed the pos- sibility of random [non-purposeful] variations; and on analysis this seems to point back once more to the same scientific assumption of distinct co-operating forces. So far then as Darwinism really or neces- sarily implies chance, it is not discredited as a science among sciences. All of them do something similar. There are, of course, further questions as to the ultimate validity of the scientific analysis, but these questions belong to the domain of philosophy. Thirdly, however, Darwin's phrase, " natural selec- tion," lays greater stress upon the element of chance than his own facts warrant. He speaks as if the eliminating agency of a disconnected environment were the one thing valuable. In a sense he may be said to have made it probable that an element of chance (co-existence) enters into the evolutionary process. But that gives him no right to say that evolution is " due to " chance co-existence. A spark, along with fitting proportions of oxygen and hydro- gen, produces water; but you would throw little light upon the nature of water by isolating one of the factors in its production, and by describing the liquid as "due to" a spark. Salt improves soup, but it would be a fool's enterprise to set about making soup from salt. 206 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in IV Before we go on to test the applicability of natural selection to human affairs we may do well to ask whether, in the interpretation of physical nature, " natural selection " is not invoked in different senses. We are haunted by ambiguity. " Darwin- ism " is an ambiguous expression. The central con- tribution of Darwin to evolutionary theory was the doctrine of natural selection ; yet that by itself is hyper-Darwinism ; in the master's hands Darwinism means natural selection plus use-inheritance plus sex- ual selection ; these three, at any rate. So, when natural selection is used as a synonym for Darwinism, it must prove most ambiguous. May we take for granted that variation is non-telic and yet constitutes new species ? Let us call this natural selection A. Are we to regard natural selection merely as a force that prevents relapse by weeding out possible evil specimens? Let us call this natural selection B. Or are we to regard it as a positive source of prog- ress when in alliance with other evolutionary forces (telic variation, use-inheritance, sexual selection, a more general working of intelligence ; all these are candidates for the position) — secondary to them, and accelerating their operation ? 1 Let us call this 1 The intelligent reader will easily perceive that the analysis in the text is far from being final. Is A everything? That is hyper-Darwin- ism. Is A something but not everything? That view might be held. Is A a logical possibility in some departments — rather unlikely to be a fact in any? That is the view argued in these pages, — and so forth. I trust, however, that all the distinctions have been taken which are necessary for our argument — in addressing intelligent readers. CHAP, xvn METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 2O? natural selection C. Or, recurring to our first point (letter A), are we to leave the question open what the tendency of individual variations may be ? In that case the meaning of "natural selection" will hover between A and C. This last ambiguity is per- haps the worst of all. It leads to the insinuating or implying of A by evolutionists when they are not prepared to affirm it definitely and still less to prove it. Too often when C, or even the truism B, is established, we are asked to admit that "natural selection " has been proved. Indeed, the whole pro- cess (C) is habitually treated as if natural selection not merely entered into it but were necessarily and everywhere the dominant factor in it — -as if C were A; as if progressive evolution, in which natural selection plays some part, might safely be called "progress by natural selection."1 It is natural selection A — the natural selection which, according to hyper-Darwinism, stands alone — that incurs the gravest suspicion of relying upon chance in lieu of reason. And it is mainly, though not wholly, natural selection A that we shall have to keep in view after this. It is natural selection A that we cannot toler- ate in human affairs — least of all in morality and religion. Natural Selection B is a fact. — Natural selection — A, B, or C — means primarily "struggle" and 1 The reader will please note that we are not repeating our objec- tion, developed in Part III. of this chapter. Even although we con- ceded Darwin's right to speak of natural selection A, if it exists, as leading to " evolution by natural selection," we must still complain of his (and his friends') question -begging and misleading usage in speak- ing so not only of A but of C, 208 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m partial survival — viz. survival of the best (in one respect or in another). I cannot think that, since Malthus and Darwin, any one has the right to deny the existence of a selective process in nature ; and one of its effects must also be admitted — its effect in keeping each separate species up to the highest point of efficiency (natural selection B). In one sense therefore, even if hardly more than a truism, we make bold (as our first step) to affirm that natural selection exists. Nattiral Selection, C or A, is also to be regarded as a reality. — Perhaps the following consideration may enable us to take another step forward. Science now seems to teach that organic evolution is a fact, — that, in spite of their apparent fixity and distinctness, species have somehow grown out of each other, and, presumably, are growing still. Then, if that be so, and if a selective process among organisms is simul- taneously taking place, the two processes must have affected each other (C) if they were not really one process (A). In other words: if, from any cause whatever, variations capable of building up a new species are coming into existence, and if it is impossi- ble that all organisms should live out their full span, then the new varieties will be weeded, and weeded selectively, like the rest, and this process must at least contribute something towards maturing the slowly evolving types (C ; but A is possible), as well as towards maintaining in efficiency organisms of the types already constituted (B). Now, if this consider- ation be admitted, we may narrow the problem. We need no longer ask, Does natural selection exist ? Or even, Does it exist as a cause of progress ? We ask, CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 2OQ Is it the only cause ? In an evolving world B implies C as a minimum, and suggests A as a possibility. Does A anywhere actually exist ? Does natural se- lection anywhere operate by itself alone ? That is our narrowed problem. That is our burning ques- tion. One school will say, Natural selection is so strong a force that we need postulate no other besides it. Another school will reply, Natural selection is perfectly credible as an auxiliary or accelerating force, but perfectly incredible as the only force. Soup (once more) is the better for a handful of salt, but you will never make salt into soup. If selection gets hold of a good thing it knows how to keep hold of it, or even how to push it on ; but it can originate nothing. It will also be possible to hold an opinion midway between these extremes. " Natural selection " by itself may be a conceivable cause of distinct species, yet it may be thought that other causes exist in nature which do the work more rapidly (Natural Selection A possible ; plurality of causes comes in, and Natural Selection C is the actual process). Analysis of Natural Selection C. — The example of one concrete force assumed to be working in com- bination with natural selection may make our mean- ing clearer. Let us take use-inheritance. Lamarckism and Darwinism can be held separately, or they may be united ; but [we have argued that] since Darwin has pointed to natural selection no one can reason- ably ignore it or utterly deny it. If we are to be Lamarckians at all, we must now be Darwinian Lamarckians. We may differ from Darwin as to the relative value of the two forces. Probably any direct evolutionary force which exists and operates must 210 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in count for much more in the result than the indirect force of natural selection which co-operates with it. Nevertheless, natural selection must be producing some effect, if any process for the evolution of species is going on. If use-inheritance is working for evolution, natural selection will back it up in two ways, distinguishable from each other if not objectively distinct. Cases of relapse by " Atavism," below the standard already reached, will be wiped out ; natural selection will be a safeguard or rear guard to the process of evolution (Natural Selection B). And secondly, in proportion as the competition is keener, natural selection will do more and more to accelerate the process in a positive sense. As between the fuller and the less full instances of use-inheritance — the greater and less reproduction of serviceable " acquired qualities " — natural selection will (cceteris paribus) steadily award the prize to those specimens which most fully repre- sent the working of use-inheritance (Natural Selec- tion C in the proper sense). Another question might be asked here. Can we have Natural Selection A and Natural Selection C as distinct co-operating agencies ? Can natural selection in Darwin's favourite sense work as a part of the evolving forces in addition to its effect in the way of accelerating some other force ? Surely this can only be the case if in part of the field it is the only force ; i.e. if certain qualities are exempt from the operation of the more powerful co-operating evolutionary force. Even if you can imagine non-serviceable variations being presented along with others, the fruit of a dis- tinct evolutionary force, which are serviceable from the CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 2 1 1 very outset, it is almost incredible that natural selec- tion A should winnow the non-serviceable variations so as to secure an advantageous remainder of any appreciable size. Any other evolutionary force which co-operates with natural selection must eclipse it as a rival, though it may welcome it as an ally. We can- not add the working of natural selection to the working (in the same field) of any directly telic force. But natural selection may multiply the results of the other force — if competition is keen enough. Let us try to go one step further still. As long as struggle lasts — natural struggle — struggle plus elimination,1 natural selection is still at work. A force may come to the birth in the process of evolu- tion — shall we say, of evolution by natural selection ? — which eclipses natural selection itself in importance. According to Professor Lloyd Morgan, animal intelli- gence is a force of this kind. It is " far more rapid " than natural selection.2 Biologically, it must be regarded as an intensifying of one valuable quality, "plasticity," or adaptiveness and modifiability in the individual organism. The more intelligent, the more adaptable ; hence man, who possesses reason, is the most adaptable of all animals, and has spread over the whole world. Intelligent modifiability is inher- ited, as it were, in blank. Use-inheritance [not in blank] is improbable ; it seems unlikely, says Pro- fessor Lloyd Morgan, that " habit " is inherited in later 1 Mr. Sutherland may be said to plead for elimination in the human race, but not for struggle ; Mr. Kidd for struggle but not for elimina- tion. And each of them calls his mutilated remainder natural selec- tion! 2 Evidently natural selection A is assumed — non-telic variation. 212 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in generations as an organic " instinct." 1 Abstract modifiability is transmitted, in the form of intelligence ; individual adjustment, helped by teaching, — by the slender fund of animal " tradition," — does the rest. Yet even here, where a new force has arisen, natural selection is not abolished. The new force must, I take it, blend with natural selection, so long as struggle lasts. There will be now three effects of natural selection — (i) guarding the rear — killing off stupid members of the f amliy ; (2) pushing on the van (killing off the less clever too); (3) giving a prefer- ence to the intelligent stock as a stock over non-intelli- gent or less intelligent competitors of an adjacent stock. This is a new point. It is another phase of Natural Selection C. We make a separate heading for it because it brings out most clearly the presence of intelligence as a new evolutionary force, or, otherwise regarded, as a new and advantageous quality. Some will describe the appearance of a new force or quality as being due to Natural Selection A ; we have explained above why we dislike speaking of new qualities as being " due to " natural selection. There is yet a further sense in which natural selection continues to work. We claim that even intelligent animals are affected by natural selection (A?) — at least in regard to their physique. It is 1 I am sorry that I have failed to understand Professor Morgan's subtler suggested substitute for use-inheritance. I cannot see how it dif- fers from simple natural selection {Habit and Instinct, chap. xiv.). Are the modifications postulated in the organism anything more than changes coincident with the variations in the germ ? How are they conditions of variation? Does not the selecting environment do everything — upon this hypothesis of Professor Morgan's? CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 213 not in animals but only in man that we are told of an " arrest of the body." The old sort of struggle continues in the higher brutes, and the old lines of progress are prolonged. In one respect therefore the old and the new forces, the slow and the swift, are added to each other; in another respect, — if we look to the growth of intelligence alone, — the two forces must be said to blend. And the blend- ing is in part an interference or a conflict. To a certain extent, intelligence is so thoroughly novel as to hamper its older comrade. If birds build nests not by instinct but by teaching, stupid birds which would otherwise have died off will learn the essentials of life (like stupid men), and survive ! So far, then, natural selection is thwarted. But only so far. It is not until Intelligence has become Reason that it proves strong enough to suspend natural selection. Among the animals, struggle still lasts, and the stupid bird will die out or " tend " to die out in times of difficulty ; though it will not vanish so promptly as it would have done if there had been no intelligence in the case, and if natural selection, or what is called natural selection, had been lord of all. The intelligent race will gain additional marks as against all non-intelligent races ; within the intelligent race itself, the prize will still go to the best — to the cleverest or swiftest or strongest. Can we finally decide whether or not we ought to believe in A as an actual process ? Is there any region in which " natural selection " acts alone ? Or — more broadly — is it legitimate to regard natural selection A as the great evolutionary force in nature? 214 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in It looks like a question of figures. Are there can- didates enough ? Is the " pluck " sufficiently severe ? You may get enough of your chosen sort out of any random bunch of samples — if it is big enough. That is one view. Others again might affirm that the question is not one of numbers but of time. In (almost) endless time, any bunch that is regularly furnished will grow big enough by accu- mulation. Here Mr. Sutherland gives us one shred of evi- dence; and perhaps we may be able to make use of it even if we do not dogmatically decide to re- gard natural selection as "a question of figures." The evidence is this, that the higher races in nature, when they produce offspring, follow a method of quality, not quantity. That implies that, in the higher races, natural selection, even if not sus- pended, has at least incomparably less room to work in. Yet evolutionary advance has certainly not been slower in these, the characteristically highest forms ! This fact does not seem very favourable to what is claimed for natural selection A, that we ought to regard it as a reality, and perhaps as the dominant reality in evolution. For either — (1) Though natural selection was predominant lower down, some new mysterious force has now been disengaged, which [more than ?] replaces it. A has become C ; or else (2) If, where the best evolutionary results are gained, natural selection cannot do much, we may hesitate to believe that it produces much effect at any part of the process. There must be other CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 21 5 forces; telic variation and use-inheritance are can- didates. Not A anywhere ; C everywhere.1 To repeat our conclusions then; natural selection (A) is certainly not the only principle of evolution in nature. It is very doubtful whether there is any part of the field where it stands alone (whether natural selection A exists), though it seems meta- physically possible ; i.e. the supposition seems to be sense and not nonsense. On the other hand it is certain that the law of natural selection (B and especially C) is at work, with large effects, in every part of what is strictly called Nature. In the next place, we have to approach the cen- tral part of our subject, by asking how far natural selection is applicable to human evolution. Here as elsewhere the burning question is whether nat- ural selection A can be applied to human affairs. But we must keep all three forms in view — A, B, and C. We must also distinguish between the biological 1 An odd suggestion offers itself. Can we combine Mr. Sutherland and Professor Lloyd Morgan ? Can we hold that the higher animals are able to advance with less help from natural selection, because they have more help from their intelligence? One must note a distinc- tion ; physical evolution by means of intelligence is not identical with the evolution of rational intelligence, which Drummond, etc., believe " arrests " the body. Higher brute races are certainly intelligent, and (I suppose) are certainly evolving physically. — Dr. Mellone (Studies, etc.) puts a different construction on the whole question. He inclines to assume a psychical factor in all evolution, even of plants, — on Wundt's view, that plants are descended from animated ancestors! This is very un-Darwinian. 2l6 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART m view of man — where natural selection is most likely to be at home — the sociological view, and the moral view. Man is still an animal, an organism, though he is also a citizen and a moral agent. First, then, biologically, does natural selection ap- ply to man ? l The Struggle with the Beasts. — When we read in the Bible of man's dominion over the creatures, we naturally think of domesticated animals, or of those wild species which man — and woman — make use of for food, clothing, ornament, etc. But man's suprem- acy over savage and powerful animals is a far more wonderful fact. There must have been a period of sharp conflict. Even in the Old Testament (to quote it again) we have traces of the dread lest wild beasts should gain the upper hand, and make human life heavy with torturing anxiety. The conflict ended however in a decided victory for the seemingly weak race of man. His dominion became a reality. His fear and the dread of him affected even the most for- midable among his animal subjects. It was fixed that his life should follow its regular course, unhindered on any great scale by the evil beasts. They could only carry on a guerilla warfare. When they slay a man, it is an " accident," and, in spite of such excep- tions, the human race marches bravely onward. Men have emerged from this struggle for existence. The 1 The " Arrest of the Body " seems to imply that physical evolution is at an end, and therefore that the force of natural selection, which makes for evolution, is also at an end. And in the closing chapter we shall quote names of high authority who deny that natural selection applies to man or at least to civilised men — Darwin, Professor K. Pear- son, Professor Lloyd Morgan. But it may be well that we should here look for ourselves into the details, and form our own judgment. CHAR xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 2 1/ struggle continues beneath them ; but they, with what- ever limitations and exceptions, are victors, and cham- pions of the world. Concurrently, they have learned — again, with certain limitations and exceptions — not to struggle a entrance against each other. There follows from these two attainments (once again, with some strange and saddening exceptions among the lower human races) that man has the awful preroga- tive and solemn privilege of dying a natural death. Such a thing is rare in the animal world ; but men drink their cup of pain to the last drop, and pass, it may be, with unbandaged eyes behind the veil, into the unseen. Famine. — Emergence from struggle with animal competitors may signify nothing better than a liberty to die of famine. Natural selection does not govern the physiological development of men, for they have not overfilled the world ; but a local and temporary over-population not infrequently arises, and famine follows close upon it. Civilisation ought to have other means of coping with such an overplus ; nature treats it as a normal case of animal superabundance, and falls to selecting again by the old eliminating methods. The human harvest is weeded ; the strongest survive, weakened — probably not permanently injured ; others succumb. Here then is natural selection at work among men, and conceivably Natural Selection A, if Natural Selection A anywhere exists. Of course it will be much hampered, more hampered than among any of the animals, by the comparatively low rate of fecundity in man, though famine goes a certain way towards remedying that. Among the higher animals, as we saw, evolution has continued no less markedly 2l8 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in than with the lowest, and we decided that some other factor making for progress must be in operation there besides natural selection (A). We have no similar assurance that biological evolution in the sense of progress is continuing among men — have we not heard of the " arrest of the body " ? If evolution continues it must owe its strength to something be- sides the recurrence of famine. That is not frequent enough. It does not " eliminate " severely enough to enforce progress, even if it tends that way. On the other hand, famine has been no rare thing among savages — no rare thing even in the history of the civilised world. For good or for evil, elimina- tion has acted on mankind through this agency ; and yet every civilised government, even the hardest, is ashamed of famine, and overwhelmed with a sense of defeat when its people are starved. Probably, if famine were allowed to stalk the world unchecked, we should see the selection of a corresponding physi- cal type in the human races ; a low type ; prolific ; tenacious of bare existence ; never rising much above the margin of subsistence and possible survival. The upward path lies elsewhere. Pestilence is another eliminating agency which takes the weak and spares the strong, though it is much more likely than famine to leave behind it dan- gerous and enfeebling " dregs " in those who recover. It has been supposed, indeed, that the Jewish race owes some of its health to the fact that the hideously insanitary conditions of the mediaeval ghettos killed off the weak. Strange if the most sanitary and the least sanitary conditions should alike result in pro- ducing a healthy human type ! But there seems CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 2 19 every probability that the Jews were already one of the toughest of human stocks when they entered that furnace. They emerged hardened still further ; ordinary human races might have succumbed. If we fell back on "natural selection," not sanitation, to make our people healthy, we might succumb ! It is not to be denied that pestilence is relatively advantageous. If the world must go on under con- ditions of filth, it is better for the race that the resulting diseases should blaze up in intermittent epidemics, carrying off the weakest, than that they should linger on as a chronic leaven of weakness and pain, tainting the whole race. But it rests upon us to find a better system than the serviceable pesti- lence. I say again in all seriousness, if we selfishly fell back upon laissez faire, natural selection might eliminate us all. Civilisation may well have softened our fibre in some respects ; and homo sapiens has no title-deeds to life guaranteeing him its continuance. Of all conceptions of the end of the (human) world, none perhaps could be more ghastly than the vision of a race dwindling away, from vice, from self- indulgence, from inherited disease — a race that could not rise to the responsibilities of reason and conscience, but called " sauve qui peut " when danger came, with the result that from the ensuing stam- pede none escaped without fatal injuries. If we fall too low, wise nature will simply stamp out all of us. And yet we have in pestilence, while it lasts, an accessory selecting agency (Natural Selection C), with the drawback noted, that the monster leaves the mark of his talons upon many who escape with their lives. 22O FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in Vice. — Mr. Sutherland lays much stress upon the excellent results due to elimination of the vicious. This is of course Natural Selection B, and nothing more. Prolong to infinity the elimination of vicious persons — will that develop virtue ? At least it would not, upon any view, improve its quality. Another favourite idea is that any special vice, if left un- checked— -e.g. drunkenness — will burn itself out by natural selection. Dr. G. A. Reid's " Present Evolu- tion of Man"1 argues for this pleasing possibility. Surely this is folly. Men are not of distinct kinds, as the old Gnostics supposed. We can acquire quali- ties by developing their germs ; we can make the transition from the class of the sober to that of the drunken. It is only too easy! Frightful as are the penalties of such vice, when have they proved sufficient to counteract the charms of jollity and good fellowship, and of a " moderation " which so easily becomes immoderate? Mr. Sutherland him- self implies that each generation or two develops its own criminal class, its own profligates. Assuredly upon that point he is credible. Human nature is versatile, and man is weak ; a new crop of drunkards may easily be grown as the old ones die out. If you leave everything to natural selection, that is how the world will go. Crime, or human justice punishing crime, is also a form of Natural Selection B. Eighty or a hundred years ago criminals were " eliminated " wholesale, with little profit to society ! The problem of human advance proves unexpectedly complex. Brutal vio- lence on the part of the law provoked more crime 1 Quoted in Habit and Instinct and elsewhere. OF "HE UNIVERSITY CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS J0F NATURAJ/SELECTION 221 than it repressed. Even at the present day, how- ever, we do some "eliminating." We hang a few criminals, and we seclude others, both men and women, for long terms of imprisonment, during which terms at least it is impossible for them to pro- duce offspring. We may attribute these results to Natural Selection if only in this sense, that the re- duction or checking of population was not the design of our criminal law, but an incidental consequence. It is a favourite idea with some students of society that " the sterilisation of the unfit " ought to be car- ried very much farther. Theoretically, one is tempted to sympathise with the opinion, but it is doubtful whether any such mechanical methods will do much for human welfare. War is among the strangest and saddest of man's institutions. Systematised violence and wholesale slaughter are new things in the animal world. War has been immensely widespread and potent in the course of human development. Socially, we saw that, as between community and community, war has often done good. In early days the best fighters are generally the best tribe ; and war has not infrequently become a pioneer of civilisation. But, alas ! at what a cost! Morally and socially, the cost is beyond reckoning. And biologically, or in its bearing on individuals, war has usually snatched away the fittest and left the weak or the cowards to become the parents of the next generation. In early days, when individual valour counted for much, war exercised some influence in the way of selecting the best — backed as it was by a sexual selection ; redcoats have always charmed the gentler half of the race. But in 222 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in recent times the characteristic effect of war is down- right evil, as when the Napoleonic campaigns (it is supposed) lowered the stature of the whole French nation. War is a selecting agency of great influence turned upside down. Religious Celibacy has possibly had more conse- quences, good or bad, in its moral and social than in its physiological bearings, and it is a historical rather than a natural force ; still it may be mentioned here for convenience. When you take account of Buddh- ism as well as of Christianity, you perceive that re- ligious celibacy has been a phenomenon on a vast scale, and with a gigantic influence, like war. Like war, too, it has selected steadily in the wrong direc- tion. The best and finest spirits were withdrawn from family life ; the inferior types were left to per- petuate their qualities in offspring. We see then that famine may possibly show the working of Natural Selection A within narrow limits ; pestilence and disease, if they do anything positive, must be ranked in Natural Selection C, as mere ac- cessories to some better force ; the fatal or sterilising consequences of vice and crime do no more than pro- tect the rear — Natural Selection B ; war and religious celibacy select, but select pretty steadily on the wrong side. It does not appear therefore that natural selection achieves much for progress, or much even for ad- vance of any kind, in any one definite direction, within human affairs, when viewed biologically. The view of natural selection implied in the doctrine of the " arrest " of the human " body " is upon the whole confirmed. CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 223 But, if it were the best thing in the world, man- kind cannot make use of natural selection. We must keep each other alive and well, as far as we may ; humanity insists upon it. In point of fact, the civilised races are putting their chief reliance, for biological progress or safety, upon forces of a very different kind. There is first — for we are speaking here of man's physique — the provision, by laws and by administration, of a sanitary material environment; next comes the advance of medical skill, the diffusion of medical and sanitary knowledge, public opinion, law (requiring and forbidding certain individual acts), morality, religion. That is the line we must move on, whether we like it or not. And we have no reason whatever to suppose that we should get better results by " following nature " in a more brutal fashion. In sociology Mr. Benjamin Kidd has claimed that all our salvation lies in natural selection, failing which " panmixia " entails retrogression. This is really bio- logical rather than sociological doctrine, and probably or certainly it is bad biology. There is little or no true struggle for existence among human beings ; thank God for that ! Reason and our moral nature make it impossible ; and yet we seem to have escaped retrogression. Mr. Kidd dwells on the necessity of struggle, while he says nothing about elimination ; and he applies his supposed biological truths directly to the human animal. Reason is held to affect the process chiefly in a dangerous way. It makes men clever, no doubt, but it makes them too selfish to strug- gle in the interests of the species, unless religion had come in to keep us up to the mark. Social evolution 224 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in therefore depends on (what is called) natural selection, minus reason, \>\\\.plus religion. So Mr. Kidd tells us. We should say that it depends upon reason plus morality///^ religion. And since it depends on rea- son, it depends on those who have reason most fully, and yet are brothers to those who have least of it ; in other words, social progress depends upon great men. We lesser men stand on their shoulders ; as reasonable beings, we share in their discoveries. On their side they are not independent of us, the little men. Even the ruthless Napoleon Bonaparte is said to have made that confession. "Why," he asked of David, "have you put those tiny troops and guns into the corner of my portrait? I ought to be alone." The embarrassed painter apologised as best he could. He thought that the sketch of the army in the background had a his- torical interest, etc., etc., when Napoleon, having re- covered his good temper, remarked, "After all I owe a good deal to these worthy little men." Well might he say so ! Finally, among the different human provinces, we have the assertion that natural selection prevails in morals. Professor Alexander alleges this of moral ideas. They struggle against each other, and the fittest sur- vive. Stripped of metaphor, the meaning is that free discussion is a condition of progress in moral thought. Surely, it is one condition. But it is a psychical con- dition ; it implies reason ; it implies the power of the great man to indoctrinate others. Mr. Alexander has not affirmed literal natural se- lection. It was impossible that he should, though in CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 22$ some respects he has gone too near it, and has thus exaggerated the mutual repulsiveness and exclusive- ness of distinct types of ethical thought. But, after all, is not the main point here just the one which Mr. Alexander (following Darwin) takes for granted ? Whence come the new varieties ? In dealing with morals, at any rate, this is all-important ; and in dealing with morals, at any rate, this cannot be answered. Even the victorious analysis of the evolu- tionist is baffled here at the central point — A spirit breatheth, and is still ; In mystery our soul abides. What one can say about new and sound moral ideas smacks painfully of platitude. Sometimes they may be championed at first by moral eccentrics. But usually the teacher will be well rooted in the past, drawing from it his best strength, seeking not to destroy, but to fulfil. Yet even he is likely to be proscribed, insulted, hated, and perhaps killed. Not till after his death will men recognise the truth of his words; then they will quote them against his successors. Mr. Sutherland deals not so much with the growth of moral ideas as with the history of moral behaviour and the growth of character. The doing of what is right concerns him rather than the knowledge of it ; these are distinct problems. His belief is that we grow better because the vicious and sensual and vio- lent die off leaving few children. If there is any other evolutionary factor, it is so paltry in extent that we may safely disregard it. Natural Selection B is to smuggle in Natural Selection A concealed in 226 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in his pocket, or is to disguise himself as his big brother. There is no such thing as a new life for the repentant sinner, and there is no influence (to speak of) between man and man. The filthy remains filthy still, and the righteous remains righteous still. We are born good, or else we are damned into the world. Elimination is first among moral forces ; the rest are nowhere. What is a truer theory of man's advance in actual goodness? We help each other — by influ- ence, example, magnetism. And inwardly we are drawn or driven to righteousness partly by the bitter- ness of sin, partly by (not the pleasures of virtue, but) the beauty of holiness. It would be impossible . to say which has the more power. The great inspiring personality who helps the multitude of little lives may be unoriginal and hackneyed in thought. It is the glow of spiritual goodness, plus a mysterious per- sonal endowment, perhaps of the nature of sympathy, that constitutes greatness and efficiency in this de- partment. But the "worthy little men" are quite as important here as the leaders. Mr. T. H. Green has told us that the Napoleonic wars were able to do some good, as well as mischief, in the world, just because of the courage and loyalty of the millions of private soldiers who were the victims of . one man's ambition. Faithfulness is the greatest of the virtues. Nor must we forget the stored wealth of the past in the form of moral institutions and traditions. We have one proof of the all-sidedness of Jesus Christ in this, that He is both the supremely original moral teacher and the supreme personal influence. He so crossed the currents of dignity and respecta- bility in His age that dignity and respectability, feel- CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 22/ ing " what such men call the * necessity ' of putting Him to death," tried — strange endeavour ! — to " eliminate " Him ! Yet without strain or manifest extravagance the view can be advanced that it was His glory to put the great moral commonplaces into circulation as " current coin." We go to Him for "sweetness and light." He is the truth. We go to Him for transforming warmth, and He makes our cold ideals live, and melts our hearts. VI Natural selection then does not rule within the sphere of reason. We may now face the question, whether it can be said to account for the first emer- gence of reason and morality ? One is reluctant to admit this. Yet it seems as if there was almost the same warrant for ascribing the emergence of reason to natural selection as for im- puting to its agency any other new thing that arises in the course of evolution. Darwin's language we have pronounced ill-balanced. Natural selection does not create. In speaking as if it did, Darwin ignores a co-operating factor of even greater consequence, the capacity for aggregate variation in the material. Moreover, selection out of non-telic elements seems possible, if at all, only in the lower ranges of evolu- tion, where fecundity is greatest. Yet it may be held that reason emerges by means of the process called natural selection, and by means of a process in which natural selection, i.e. struggle and elimination, have certainly played some considerable part. On the as- sumption of evolution all along the line, it is implied 228 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in that [what is on the surface] a natural process has led up to the spiritual forces of morality and reason. Being a natural process, it has never wholly shaken off the influence of elimination. Of course, if Mr. Wallace is right, that there was a special supernatural intervention when reason ap- peared upon earth, it will not do to say even in the most guarded sense that natural selection created reason. But this quasi " miracle " is doubtful. Mr. Wallace himself has laid the greatest stress upon the preservation of reason by natural selection. We prefer his teaching on that point, with all its difficul- ties. — Why (for example) have the irrational races not died out ? Can we hold that the race nearest man, yet irrational, died out in competition with him ? Perhaps that is why it is so hard to find traces of the missing link. Presumably competition is always keenest between adjacent forms. Consequently, de- feated species may disappear outright, and their dis- appearance may explain that semblance of a gap between the nearest existing species, which is so no- ticeable in many parts of nature. I do not know whether this suggestion has been made before. If not, it may be offered for what it is worth to those who are interested in defending natural selection. VII The view now sketched of natural selection — that it is a real force, but strictly limited — has been out- lined in a spirit of sympathy with idealistic philoso- phy. Yet it is opposed to the views of several distinguished Hegelian idealists. Some of them CHAP. XVII METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 22C) would say that it goes much too far in commenda- tion ; others, not far enough. Professor Ritchie endorses natural selection with- out putting any limit to its application. It seems to give him all that he needs. There is evolution in Darwin, and there is evolution in Hegel; therefore natural selection accounts for everything, or at least it does so mutatis mutandis. We have tried to show in detail what the mutation is, and it is pretty extensive. (On the other hand, Professor Ritchie, as social philosopher, takes the opposite view, holding that reason has transformed the whole evolutionary process which it has touched.) Dr. Stirling and Mr. Sandeman, if I understand them rightly, regard natural selection as a piece of showy but flimsy thinking, that crumbles away as you handle it. They would deny that it explains anything, or that it applies to any part of the cosmos. Mr. Sandeman1 believes thoroughly in the teleo- logical character of organisms, and finds every exist- ing species too perfect and harmonious and balanced to think of "bettering itself." Instead of the real- istic vision of cosmic horrors, he has a poet's vision of peace. He is not content with excluding absolute unfitness, but insists on denying even relative unfit- ness. "Whatever is, is right." It exists, it has sur- vived ; it triumphs ! Like the apostle Paul, Mr. Sandeman bestows more abundant comeliness upon our uncomely parts. With great force and penetra- tion he observes2 that inherited rudiments have not 1 Problems of Biology. 2 This is a valuable corrective or supplement to Professor Ritchie's criticism of Dr. Reich, Darwinism and Politics, pp. 124, 133. 230 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in been inherited as ready-made rudiments; they have been built up along with the rest of the organism, taking their full share in the reciprocities of organic growth. Ex hypothesi^ what is really (and not merely apparently and externally) useless must long ago have disappeared under the fierce strain of struggle for existence. Yes, very good. Nothing is abso- lutely unfit. The most rudimentary part must dis- charge some obscure physiological function in the rhythm of life. But are we really to suppose that the human body would be wrecked and ruined if (say) the ilium ccecum were somehow and safely evolved out of existence — as the surgeon on emer- gency may cut it out ? If such a body arose, would it not be a better body than ours, so far as hitherto evolved ? Is it unthinkable that nature should im- prove in this fashion ? Is not the whole living world relatively fit, indeed, but also, in many important details, relatively unfit, and is not an aborted organ very plainly marked by nature as, in one most impor- tant sense, unfit? Mr. Sandeman presumably implies the absolute systematic perfection of the whole universe as well as of each individual organism, and presumably affirms this postulate on metaphysical grounds. Even with- out repudiating it, we may urge that the idea is not applicable off-hand to the world of nature. Men will not readily surrender that dynamic view of nature, as a great and incomplete process, which Darwin and other evolutionary thinkers have taught us. The optimism of Mr. Sandeman's own creed does not force us to affirm the perfection of the individual organism save as a part in the process by which the perfect whole evolves itself. CHAP, xvii METAPHYSICS OF NATURAL SELECTION 23! Dr. Stirling, on the other hand, finds the individual too poor for the work required of it in Darwinism. So far as I understand his position, it has two ele- ments. It nails Darwinism to the assertion that variation is casual (as it were causeless). And while repudiating such " casual " difference as a source of progress or as a possible beginning of specific types, it alleges the existence of the casual element under the name of " individual difference," which seems to be in Dr. Stirling's 1 view all but aimless and all but causeless. Perhaps the meaning is this. Every individual differs from every other member of the species. The difference does not affect the specific type or pattern ; it neither augments nor lessens efficiency. Each is a man, a fish, a frog ; yet each has its own peculiarity, its, so to say, casual peculiarity, indifferent to the specific type. To get species — law — rational sys- tem out of this most casual, most non-systematic of all things in the cosmos — that is the alchemy of Darwinism ; out of a brew of chance, to distil pure reason ! The casual difference is just the drop of unreason, of brute matter, dropped into the specific type in order to make it down into a new individual. This, so far as I can conjecture, is Dr. Stirling's meaning. No summation of individual peculiarities can ever amount to a specific difference. The things are heterogeneous in their very essence. 1 1 am thinking of As Regards Protoplasm and Darivinianism, but mainly of Dr. Stirling's Gifford Lectures. The very acute mind of Dr. Stirling suggests innumerable objections to Darwinism. We have only dealt with what seems to be the central point — the denial that the alleged process is reasonably thinkable. 232 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART in Now I will not attempt to criticise the metaphysics of this. But I venture to assume that such thinking lies too deep for science. No biologist would hesitate to speak of "identical twins" or would admit that heredity acts differently at each birth, merely in order to put itself metaphysically in the right in its act of bringing into the world a new individual. If " heredity " should not differentiate individuals, " en- vironment " would speedily do so. On the other hand, I submit that the " casual " variation which science speaks of is found, when science sifts its thoughts, to be one which — whether actual or only possible — might quite well conceiva- bly, by cumulation, amount in time to a new specific type. Of course there are difficulties in detail under Darwinism. But is Darwinism metaphysically incom- petent ? Does Natural Selection A outrage common sense when you understand its terms ? I think not. It is certainly limited in range; it possibly exists nowhere in nature as an actual process; Darwin's name for his theory may be misleading ; but surely the theory is conceivable. Finally, let us observe that, even as a fiction, natural selection might be serviceable, though the truth were merely that species are things which might have resulted from infinitesimal changes in endless time. Even on that view " natural selection " might be a fruitful guide to investigation, not a blind alley. Per contra the fruitfulness of natural selection as a theory does not in itself certify it to be a true theory, whether in whole or in part. PART IV HYPER-DARWINISM — WEISMANN, KIDD CHAPTER XVIII An intenser assertion of struggle — Not on ground of experiment ; evi- dence is ambiguous — On ground of a theory of heredity — Darwin's theory (Pangenesis) assumed derivation of embryonic qualities from qualities and tissues of parental organisms — Use-inheritance possible or probable on this view — But " Atavism " forced the concession, some " gemmules " had passed on undeveloped from earlier genera- tions till they found their chance — Galton's figures for resemblance to ancestors — Hence theories asserting " continuity of the germ plasm" — Parable of the Hierarchy — Galton (" Stirp ") does not absolutely deny the possibility of use-inheritance — But in Weis- mann's earlier and more consistent views, founded on by Mr. Kidd, amphimixis is the only cause of variation — Extrusion of one of the " polar bodies " securing ( ?) non-identity of all offspring of same pair — Permutations and combinations of qualities of unicellular organisms — Nature selecting fittest adults, and in them best germ plasm — Parable of the suckers — Of the Nile — No new quality arises, but amount of each telling quality increases — Qualities arose originally, Lamarck fashion, from environment, when unicellular life lay open to its pressure — Unicellular organisms (propagating by fission) and germ plasm are potentially immortal — Correlation alleged between sex and (natural) death; now sex is absent from the unicellular world — Natural selection might account for the pre- dominance (if not origin} of sex if Weismann would assume the necessary competition — Romanes alleges that natural selection 233 234 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv might account for predominance of habit of dying natural death; but would not death by violence sufficiently prevent any race (im- mersed in the struggle) from falling into wholesale decrepitude ? — Origin of sex and death a mystery; or "chance" variation! or effect of molecular constitution of germ plasm ! — Weismann's appeal to " natural selection," while he denies " struggle," is meta- physical in the worst sense — Recapitulation, and note of some of Weismann's changes of opinion before 1893 — Especially this change: ENVIRONMENT MAY DO SOMETHING TO MODIFY GERM PLASM ! — Making true use-inheritance conceivable, though not in- evitable — Mr. Kidd is anachronous — Panmixia, the absence of natural selection, is held to involve retrogression; important; ques- tionable ALTHOUGH we have passed under review a reaction from Darwinism, on moral grounds, or in the moral region, yet the theory which in recent years has ex- cited most attention, both popular and scientific, is not a qualification of the Darwinian doctrine of struggle, but an intensified assertion of it. Weis- mann, like the young Rehoboam, meets all discon- tent with a stiff er front and a severer policy. " My father chastised you with whips, but I will chastise you with scorpions." Darwin laid a terrible emphasis upon struggle for existence; but he admitted other causes of progress, such as sexual selection and use- inheritance ; Weismann admits no cause of progress whatsoever, except struggle for existence ; no selec- tion of the beautiful by the instinct of sex, and above all, no inheritance of acquired qualities. Such is Weismann's position; a scientific position in regard to technical questions of biology, held by a competent and highly distinguished, though also a highly spec- ulative man of science. But the position manifestly involves or suggests inferences regarding human progress : and these are worked out with devout CHAP, xvm A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 235 fidelity, and with much ability and knowledge, by Mr. Benjamin Kidd. Primarily, the question between Darwin and Weis- mann is one of fact. Does experience confirm or does it refute belief in the inheritance of acquired qualities? Unfortunately, this question like many others is more easily put than answered. Romanes tells us (in the preface to his Weismannism) that he himself, acting under Darwin's immediate direction, instituted a long series of experiments on the point ; but that the results of these labours, which extended over several years, were never published, because the experiments " all failed,"/.*, presumably, they yielded incurably ambiguous results. " Nothing is so decep- tive as facts ; " the same facts are capable of such different interpretations. Apparently, Weismann has shown that the range of the " Lamarckian factor " was grossly exaggerated. To that extent facts openly support him. Whether he has proved that use-in- heritance does not occur at all is another question. The non-inheritance of mutilations, even such as have been persisted in by custom through age after age — Chinese foot-binding is a notable instance — furnishes a strong argument in Weismann's favour. And even hostile evidence can be robbed of much of its strength. Are there not blind fish in the mammoth caves of Kentucky, and in similar caverns elsewhere ? Have not preachers freely used this illustration of the bad results of evil habit? Yes; but if there was no premium on eyesight, fish which " happened " to be born blind would have an equal chance of living and begetting progeny with fish that saw. Give it time, and natural selection — or in the opposite case, 236 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv panmixia ; the cessation of natural selection — will produce all the results commonly attributed to use- inheritance. Use-inheritance would be a much quicker process ; but have patience with natural selection (or with panmixia), in a few tens of thou- sands of years it will do all that you require. Other suggestions are that, in dark caves, the fish which put part of its physiological capital into a superfluous sense would be positively disadvantaged by its eyes in the struggle for existence. Having wasted its resources on an inherited habit of luxury, it would fail in securing the necessaries of life. And again, Professor Ray Lankester has suggested that the fishes with good eyesight would find cracks by which they could swim away, leaving behind them only the blind or purblind. If any of these were suffering from mere accidents to their eyes, they would of course on Weismann's hypothesis beget a progeny having eyesight. But, if any had their vision con- genitally dim or dark, they would become the parents of those blind fish which we know. Thus the facts give an uncertain answer, and we are driven to make a statement of the blendings of fact with hypothesis which have been championed on one side or the other. Theories of heredity are in- vented to suit the facts, so far as known, but they lie far beneath the strata where verification is possible, at least in the present state of our knowledge. The simplest and most natural assumption is that the embryo, or its antecedents, spermatozoon and ovum, owe their qualities directly to the parental organisms. " The owl comes from the egg, but like- wise the egg comes from the owl." And this natural CHAP, xviii A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 237 assumption leaves the door open for the further as- sumption that acquired qualities will be inherited. I do not see that it compels us to hold that view. An acquired quality may be (as it were) only skin deep — • having no reaction on the inner life of the organism — not stamping its mark there, and therefore not stamping its mark on the offspring, which reproduces that inner life in a new generation. If living shells, transported from a northern sea to the Mediter- ranean, assume the same bright markings found in native Mediterranean forms, who will believe that the change, however conspicuous, is the same thing as transition to a different species ? They are still essentially the same, and their offspring will be es- sentially the same, bright if developed in the Medi- terranean, dull if developed in the north. But that the deeper qualities of the parental life are all repro- duced by it in its offspring — transferred from it to its offspring — seems to correspond best to the proved nature of an organism as a unity or system, in which all parts are in reciprocal intercourse, and the whole determines all the parts. One mark or outcome of this reciprocity will be the alternation already spoken of, owl from egg, egg from owl. Darwin represents this natural assumption; but as it occurs in him it is attended by some peculiarities due to modern science. Science is bent on finding a mechanical cause for every mechanical result, and on eschewing mysticism. The effort is laudable, if it can be carried through without injustice to the facts of organic life. But it results in a singularly self- confident materialism ; or so one is tempted to think. It analyses the organism into a bundle of qualities, 238 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv and postulates a separate speck of matter or living vibration for each quality distinguishable from the rest in human thought and speech.1 The description applies, among other hypotheses, to Darwin's " pro- visional hypothesis of pangenesis." According to Darwin's view, each part of the adult and vigorous organism gives off extraordinarily minute "gem- mules." These work their way to the parts of sex, and pass on as " packets," one paternal "packet" blending with one maternal "packet" in the embryo, and gradually reconstituting a body, each gemmule helping to build up an organ, or limb, or tissue, like that from which it sprang. Facts, however, insist on a serious qualification, the facts known as atavism. Often, or always in some features, the child resem- bles a grandparent or remote ancestor more than it resembles either parent. How is this to be explained ? Again we are forbidden to fall back on mysticism, or to omit the discovery of a physical and mechanical cause. There must be gemmules from far-away an- cestors developing in each child. It follows that in each embryo some gemmules must fail to develop, but, instead of perishing, must pass on as gemmules, with all their latent qualities ; must enter with other gemmules into new packets constituting ova or sper- matozoa, and must find their chance of development in a later generation by a triumph of atavism. Thus it is only partially true in Darwin's opinion that the parent organism and the reproductive material are in full sympathetic reciprocity. Distinct part of the latter, according to Darwin, though in this genera- 1 This criticism is urged very tellingly by Mr. George Sandeman in his Problems of Biology. CHAP, xviii A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 239 tion is not of this generation ; though living in, and by, the living body of the adult of to-day, it owes its origin to other bodies, whose qualities it hopes one day to reproduce when its chance arrives. The owl comes from the egg, but the egg comes only in part from the parent owls. Another distinct part of the living embryonic substance owes its being to older birds. Mr. Francis Galton, great experimentalist and statistician, has arrived at a formula for the higher races. One-fourth he calculates belongs to each parent, one-sixteenth to each grandparent, and the remaining aliquot part of one-fourth, I presume, to remoter generations still. It must not be supposed, however, that Galton agrees with Darwin in believing in pangenesis. His position is much more nearly that of Weismann. He can only hold that one-fourth part in each of the offspring is (on the average ?) like in quality to the father or mother, not, as Darwin might do, that the child owes its being and nature in the proportion of one-fourth to the father, and the same to the mother. By a fuller consideration of the problems of atavism, and by a growing hesitation to admit the inheritance of acquired qualities, doctrines of the continuity of the germ plasm have gained in popular- ity and acceptance. There are difficulties about the facts. In certain animals it appears that, at a very early stage in embryonic development, part of the segmented ovum is differentiated for reproductive purposes. Here then the parental germ may be styled continuous with the germs which are prepar- ing in the reproductive tissues of the growing em- bryo. But in most cases it is a long time before we 240 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv reach specialised reproductive cells. The germ cells seem to be derived, if only at this early stage in de- velopment, from somatic cells, and continuity with the past seems to be disproved in favour of reci- procity in the present. At this point, therefore, Weismann and others take a deeper plunge into sub- microscopic minuteness and unverifiable theory. They cannot prove continuity of germ cells, but noth- ing can hinder their asserting continuity of germ plasm or the like, i.e. continuity of the invisible sub- stance, believed to form part of the contents of [re- productive] cell nuclei, and to be the vehicle of hereditary qualities.1 On this view of things we must alter our parable. The owl comes from the egg — true ; but the egg (the microscopic living em- bryonic ovum) never came from the owl — never ; the owl came from the egg, and the egg came from the egg. The living hereditary substance, the as- sumed carrier of the qualities of heredity, is called by Galton " Stirp." Weismann calls it " Germ plasm," subsequently " Idioplasm," and later on introduces further refinements and subdivision. If we may take an ecclesiastical analogy, the ordinary doctrine of organic reciprocity corresponds to the Protestant doc- trine of the Church. The ministry are specialised organs of the Church, kindred to all other parts of the living Church tissue, capable, if the need arises, of being replaced by any other part without serious damage to the true life of the Church. On the other hand, " continuity of the germ plasm " corresponds 1The phrase (in the allied form, "continuity of the germ proto- plasm ") is not of Weismann's coinage, but goes back to a previous writer, Jaeger. CHAP, xvm A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 241 to the High Church doctrine of apostolical succession. Age after age the Church is made or created by the hierarchy, but the hierarchy is never made by the Church ; it is made by the antecedent hierarchy. There is no reciprocity, there is no fet/ow-sh'ip, but aristocratic superiority on the one side, and absolute dependence on the other. If the hierarchy perishes, or is interrupted, everything is lost. A strange be- lief surely ! Yet who knows ? If certain views are biologically correct, the High Church school of Chris- tians may claim to be more scientific than any others. But are these views proved, or even permissible ? In their full (and guasi-High Church) severity, these views are to be found only in Weismann's ear- lier writings, wherejie develops his more character- istic positions. " Stirp " always differed from " Germ plasm " ; for Galton always admitted a certain modi- fied action of " use-inheritance " or " the Lamarckian factor." And, along with other changes registered by Romanes in 1893, Weismann had by that time withdrawn his former doctrine of the " absolute sta- bility " — so Romanes puts it — " of the germ plasm," and had come over to Galton's view, according to which the influence of environment in originating variations, and so contributing directly to evolution- ary progress, while slight, is yet not to be denied. However, the earlier form of Weismann's views must be regarded as the more coherent and original. It is almost as interesting as a fairy tale, if possibly not much truer. To an outside critic, at any rate, Weis- mannism seems to have grown latterly after the man- ner of a false hypothesis, not after the manner of truth. It has modified itself endlessly by adding on 242 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv ingenious epicycles. Instead of leading to new gen- eralisations and broad views of things, the changes have made it complex and artificial-looking. True or false, the older Weismannism is at any rate clear, — clearer than the new. And Mr. Kidd's sociology seems to appeal to the Weismann of 1893, or of still earlier years, not to the author of the later more hesi- tating statements. At first, then, Weismann had held that germ plasm was never affected by the life of the organism in which it was temporarily lodged. It was perfectly continuous, absolutely stable.1 Yet varieties occurred ; for evolution occurred ; and there was no cause of evolution except natural selection ; and natural selec- tion could only work upon given materials. Whence then did varieties proceed? From amphimixis and from that alone ; in other words, from the processes of bisexual parentage. There was " nowhere else " for variations to come from on this early and rigid theory of Weismann's ; and the theory threw a de- lightfully definite and clear light on the cloudy prob- lem, What is the origin of variations ? No doubt there was a difficulty here. If individual variation is due simply to parentage, why are not all the off- spring of the same pair facsimiles of each other? Can science clear up this mystery ? Weismann in his early phase explained it by the extrusion of one of the two polar bodies expelled from the ovum shortly before — or more usually shortly after — fertilisation. I do not know that I understand this. Up till now, 1 Apparently the phraseology is Romanes'. To a layman it looks tautological. Romanes himself (pp. 49, 86 of Weismannistn) seems unable to keep the two terms distinct in their application. CHAP, xvm A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 243 germ plasm has been described as so continuous or so stable, that it has threatened to make all the off- spring of the same pair identical with each other if the two parental germ plasms are simply added together. But now, wise nature casts away half the qualities or potentialities of the germ plasm, when it throws away half the substance, and the dividing line is drawn at random, or at any rate is never twice the same. Weismann's later view, to which Romanes had thought that he was bound to come — and on which Romanes looks with less dis- favour— seems to involve the same difficulty. How can cell segmentation divide the germ plasm into different potentialities, corresponding to differences exhibited later in the different members of the litter or family, if we are to hold to the high stability of germ plasm ? Or how on earth can we reconcile this with the doctrine that amphimixis is the only source of variations ? Moreover, are we to understand that germ plasm, "which grows very rapidly," never grows at all, or never segments at all, after birth ? If it did, apparently it would be constantly changing its quali- ties. It would be highly z/Tzstable.1 Nature then, according to Weismann, had been playing an immense game of permutations and com- binations, if not since the dawn of life itself, yet ever since the first origin of multicellular organisms, whether plant or animal. All of these become uni- cellular at the beginning of the embryonic process, 1 The polar bodies had to serve as the explanation of a second difficulty — one of size. It also is mysterious. On it also Weismann has changed his ground. And by that change also he secures greater approbation from Romanes. 244 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv when the new life is constituted by fertilisation. And therefore " ontogeny " briefly recapitulates " phy- logeny," the individual organism passing rapidly through the stages by which evolutionists hold that the species has grown to be what it now is. The multicellular or higher organisms are only, as it were, loose appendages to certain peculiarly qualified uni- cellar organisms, like great flickering shadows of dwarfs or little children cast by a bonfire. The higher organisms perpetuate themselves qua uni- cellular. They may seem bicellular, because of the curious sexual split into male and female; but we must remember that ovum and spermatozoon com- bine in one to form a new life history. And all the future of the individual life lies in mice in that single cell. And we can further trace this determination of the qualities of maturity by the qualities of the embryo right back through the continuous germ plasm to an age when the whole world of organisms was unicellular. No fresh quality has come to any living creature since life began its ascent. All were implicitly present in the unicellular world; all have been slowly evolved and improved by nature's gigan- tic game of permutations and combinations. She has written out by degrees every possible grouping of the qualities of protoplasm, and has drawn her pen remorselessly through the inefficient ones. The favourite image or parable for this view of heredity — given e.g. by Huxley in the notes to his Romanes lecture — is that of a plant propagating itself by suckers. Root grows from root; every here and there the root sends upwards a perfect plant, a glory of leaves, flowers, fruit ; in the absence of these the CHAP, xvm A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 245 root could not be healthy ; yet plant is never derived from plant, and still less is root derived from plant ; every root is derived from root ; every plant is derived from root. Another image we might use is that of a river like the Nile, flowing through countries which can yield it no tributaries. The great river flows majestically on, essentially the same as it was many hundreds of miles up channel; imparting life wher- ever it goes, but receiving nothing. Such a river of life is "germ plasm," flowing through the genera- tions, yielding to all of them support, but never affected by them. There is, however, a difference which our images fail to bring out. On Weismann's view, evolutionary change is always at work, acting through natural selection. Permutations and combinations are always being remodelled — let us say, combinations of play- ing cards. The cards were originally dealt at the dawn of animal and vegetable life ; and no fresh kind of card has ever been introduced. Yet the " hands " with which the game is played have, on the whole, steadily improved from generation to generation, and from age to age. How is that possible ? Because these cards are alive. These cards multiply, aces begetting aces, and kings begetting kings. Many and many a hand has been torn up and flung away in the process of natural selection; and accordingly the surviving hands have become very strong — all court cards, or trumps, or powerful sequences.1 1 I do not know if Weismann means this ; but it seems to lie in the theory. Efficient begets efficient, as surely as non-efficient begets non- efficient. Quantities seem capable of indefinite improvement, though the theory admits of no fresh ultimate quality. 246 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv At the back of this process of combinations we have another — the original dealing or the original making of the cards. To what was that due ? To the Lamarckian factor, to the direct action of environ- ment, stamping itself upon the isolated living cell. There is an absolute contrast, it is assumed, between the two periods in the history of life. In the first, variations were due directly to the environment, not at all to natural selection,1 which only acts upon vari- ations submitted to it by sexual reproduction. In other words, environment may be called the judge in natural selection, but there is no need of environment as a judge when it is itself the maker of the things to be judged. If it is the maker, it gives a guarantee along with its goods. If or so far as Lamarckism is true, Darwinism, with its " natural selection," becomes secondary if not superfluous, ranking at best as an auxiliary and accelerating force. Thus, if the uni- cellular organism bears the stamp of environment, it has directly adjusted itself to the conditions of life ; it is already certified as " fit to survive." But, in the second great period, we are to believe that environ- ment is helpless and natural selection omnipotent. This is less arbitrary than it seems. In the unicellular age the living creature is all surface, and, as it were, at the mercy of environment. But in the multicellular age the really vital matter, the " germ plasm," is supposed to be carefully hidden away inside a body and out of reach — hidden within a body and even (the theory says) independent of its vicissitudes, so long as the body lives. The only way in which nature can now affect germ plasm is by killing off 1 So Weismann as stated by Romanes. CHAP, xvni A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 247 the body in which it resides, under sentence of "unfitness." Thus indirectly — natural selection is always indirect — and slowly — indirect processes of course are slow — evolution is pushed on. For in this fashion germ plasm is progressively improved ; and unicellular embryos, needing nothing from the mother beyond nourishment 1 up to and after birth, come to contain in themselves the promise and potency of reason, of genius, of greatness — of a Shakespeare or a Darwin. A little speck of matter, indistinguishable to human study from one of the lowest forms of life, and essentially nothing but one of these lowest forms, redistributed or regrouped, contains in itself what will necessarily ("bar" the accident of death) give the difference of a man from a beast, of a genius from a fool, of a saint from a scoundrel, or vice versa. So runs the doctrine. We have not yet stated Weismann's ingenious theory that the germ plasm, and unicellular organisms in general, are potentially immortal. Unicellular or- ganisms grow by fission ; the child is a part of the parent; it is impossible to say, after the split has been accomplished, which is child and which is parent. Both are both ; or neither is neither ! The category or conception of parentage belongs to a higher sphere of life, and is inapplicable here. If either survives — and we are assuming the continuance of the species — both may survive. Each member of the race is potentially immortal. Never a natural death, but a violent death always, must weed its ranks. If germ 1 Heredity is equal from the two parents. It seems therefore that Weismannism must be right in denying that the foetus draws anything beyond nourishment from the mother organism. 248 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART IV plasm exists at all in continuity, it is hardly necessary to argue that the same thing must be true of it. Part of the germ plasm builds up a body, and undergoes in somatic form the doom of death ; part of the germ plasm survives as germ plasm, multiplying and re- plenishing itself (if only during embryonic growth), and ultimately — in some fortunate fragments — pass- ing into new lives. This thing need never die. Most of it will die; what is transformed into body, and what fails of attaining to fertilisation. But it need not die ; it is potentially immortal. So to say, the old original germ plasm may hand on the duty of building up a body to some of the more newly formed material, and, evading the chances of death, may refuse to quit the parental tissues till the moment of fertile sexual intercourse. It is potentially immortal ; practically, by the law of chances, it will be both mortal and short-lived. If pollen grains depend on the wind or depend on insects for doing their work, how much potentially immortal " germ plasm " must die in the history of every dioecious plant ! Unicellular creatures, however, are immortal, ac- cording to Weismann, rather qua non-sexual than qua unicellular. Sex and death are somehow corre- lated ; he believes that he has proved this by show- ing a general correspondence between the age at which species produce offspring and their natural term of life. This view of Weismann 's is widely ac- cepted. A correlation between the fact of sex and the habit of dying a natural death is largely admitted. Death, then, as a natural and certain event, arose with sex, or in consequence of it. But how did sex originate ? Romanes asserts a self-contradiction in CHAP, xvin A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 249 Weismann, because at one time he says that the origin of sex was due to natural selection, at another time that it could not be. In Weismann's system, natural selection works upon the materials furnished to it by sexual reproduction — upon the new varieties thus invented — upon the new permutations or com- binations of germ plasm, thus manifested, and brought up for judgment in the form of offspring. Still, I see no reason why natural selection should not sit in judgment upon sex itself, if sex somehow originated. No doubt the admission must then be made that Weismann's clear theory of variation had ceased to be available. Sex explains other variations ; what is to explain sex ? It must presumably itself have been a new variation when it appeared for the first time in a sexless world. Once it had appeared, it might well predominate. If some multicellular organisms propagated sexually, and others non-sexually, and if some of the offspring of sexual unions proved supe- rior in the struggle to any of their competitors, why then sex would be selected by nature^ as advanta- geous ; the sexual specimens would tend to be the only ones that survived and reproduced their kind. The origin of sex, accordingly, would still be veiled in deep darkness. Weismann could say little more than that it " happened " to occur. That is very much what he does confine himself to saying "in the present state of our knowledge." Yet it appears perfectly logical to say, not that natural selection brought sex into being ; natural selection originates nothing; it chooses between competing candidates ; 1 May we say that, upon the whole, it is selected by nature, at least for the higher forms of life ? 250 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv but that, from the first and until now, natural selec- tion has favoured sex, and has made it the pre- dominant reproductive method. This seems to be perfectly fair, if Weismann is willing to postulate the true condition of natural selection, viz. competi- tion ; in this case, competition between sexual and non-sexual forms. But I am afraid that may not be so. In view of Weismann' s attitude towards the question of the origin of (natural) death,1 one must concur in Romanes' criticism, that " ultra Darwinians use the term ' natural selection ' with extreme laxity." The condemnation might be even more severely expressed. As to the origin of death, I must confess to find- ing the theory most unsatisfactory. Of course we are speaking of the origin of the habit of dying a natural death. Death by accident, death as prey, death (possibly ?) by disease, may all be assumed, in- dependently of this new and advantageous habit of retiring the seniors at a (roughly) fixed period. The new habit is said by Romanes to be advantageous for this reason, because, if multicellular (or, as he says, if sexual) organisms lived through ages, they would all become broken down and decrepit as the result of accident. For the life of me, I cannot see why this should be true. If there was any emergency with which unaided natural selection was able to deal, I should have said it was this one imaginary danger. Will the poor old things not be overtaken by their enemies ? Will they not starve from their prey 1 See the paragraphs which follow. Of course, if there is a correlation of sex and death, the new question is really the same under a different CHAP, xvm A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 251 escaping them, or being taken from them by younger competing creatures of their species who are not run down by accident or infirmity ? Have we any reason to believe that natural death — death from old age — has ever been common in the animal world (in plants, perhaps, yes) ; or have we any reason to regret its absence ? But, if it plays a scanty part, how could it secure the attention or obtain the approval of select- ing nature ? Next let us ask, how we can conceive of the pro- cess of selection being accomplished ? Race A is competing against race B. The prize is fitness to survive ; the penalty, of course, is just death. But race A, being clever enough to invent the habit of dying a natural death, therefore survives, while race B, which refuses to die unless by force, is therefore extinguished. This is not altogether such an Irish bull as it sounds. It may be held that a habit in any species of dying a natural death will produce a more efficient average individual. And so it might be possible, given the conditions, to think out the mechanism of the process. Here also, of course, natural selection does not originate the habit in question ; in this case dying. Death may be, as Weismann seems to hint, in obscure physiological correlation with the condi- tions of sexual reproduction. It may be put down as a " chance," i.e. until now an unexplained varia- tion. l One race " happened " to begin dying off, and profited thereby qua race. From it sprang all 1 Use-inheritance will do nothing here. A habit of dying, after it has been acquired, assuredly cannot be transmitted to offspring ! 252 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv the winning species, or else the same thing " hap- pened " over and over again. Death might also be said to be involved in certain permutations and com- binations of the germ plasm. That is the beauty of this unknown and unknowable substance. Nobody can say what it may not imply. If a rearranged pro- tozoon implies a Beethoven or a Shakespeare, if it gives him his programme, " Be thou among the great- est of the sons of men," molecular rearrangement in a germ cell may well imply the simpler programme, " Thou shalt surely die." And so, if he likes, Weis- mann may claim this memorable " variation," natural death, as due to the cause by which he seeks to ex- plain the origin of all variations. That, however, is not Weismann's line. Instead of that he protests that, in calling natural selection the cause of death, he does not mean to imply any com- petition between naturally mortal and potentially im- mortal stocks. Then pray what right has he to talk of natural selection ? Let us go back to first princi- ples. How does Darwin's title-page define natural selection ? As " the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life." If there is no struggle for life, and no preservation of a favoured race, neither is there any natural selection. Weismann's usage is worse than "extreme laxity." It aims at finding something cabalistic in natural selection, something talismanic. He must be reminded that, according to Comte, "nature" is the supreme example of an empty abstraction by which " metaphysical " persons think to explain phenomena, while giving no explana- tion at all. Weismann is a " metaphysician " of that type. He uses the phrase in lieu of an explanation, CHAP, xvm A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 253 not knowing, and not caring to know, what he means by it. In taking leave of Weismann's fairy tale, it may be desirable to name one by one his characteristic posi- tions, and to add in regard to each whether he still retained it in 1893, or had modified it, or had can- celled it. First, Weismann used to hold that protozoa and protophyta — unicellular nucleated plants and ani- mals, the lowest forms of life known to us — were exempt from natural selection, and were subject to the agency of environment as a source of variations. Convinced by the experiments and arguments of other writers that conjugation and natural selection were both at work in these creatures, he has come to postulate still simpler forms of life unknown to ob- servation — creatures without even a nucleus — creatures (though not the only creatures) which are potentially immortal. Now, it is an immense weak- ness to have to postulate unknown forms of the living organism. Yet perhaps it may be contended that this one addition to the theory is sufficiently logical and coherent. Even in the protozoa and protophyta, as an unscientific person might say, " germ plasm " is hidden away in a nucleus, if not behind the wall of a special cell. In purely homogeneous living organ- isms, if such existed, all parts must share and share alike in the interactions between organism and en- vironment. Weismann held that the protozoa and protophyta were potentially immortal; also the germ plasm. All these positions stand, or stood, up to the date of 1893. 254 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv He held that sex originated in the course of evolu- tion, and was absolutely due, whatever that might mean, to natural selection. This he still maintained. A similar view had been broached by him as to natural death ; he still maintained it. He had formulated a doctrine of "germ plasm." This has been modified, refined, elaborated, re-christ- ened, and, in fact, transformed more than once, both before and after 1893. But this and other technical changes of great importance do not sensibly affect the " fairy tale," nor the basis of Mr. Benjamin Kidd's social gospel, preached by him in the name of Weis- mann. We do not therefore dwell upon these changes. Next there is a group of three very important points, which imply each other, and stand or fall to- gether ; that amphimixis is the only cause of varia- tions ; that environment is impotent to originate them, in view of the "continuity" and "absolute stability " of the germ plasm ; that every higher and highest organism is simply a unicellular organism of an improved or rearranged kind, with its appendages and necessary consequences. The central point here is the stability of the germ plasm. Weismann gives that up (1893). The second point of our present group of three is therefore gone. In consequence the first point must be at least modified, and it turns out to be absolutely inverted. Amphimixis is never to be the cause of variations ; they are to go back to differences and irregularities in nutrition. At the same time, by a curious codicil, Weismann insists that these differences could never become effective unless when they were cumulated by amphimixis. Accord- CHAP, xvm A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 255 ing to Romanes, this is simply a piece of obstinacy designed to show that, if Weismann was certainly half in the wrong, yet he may have been half in the right. Romanes therefore thinks it is to be dismissed as an unproved and improbable assumption. The third point also falls to the ground. The germ plasm of one of the higher plants or animals or men is not simply a one-celled creature rearranged ; it is such a creature, if you like, but modified as well as rearranged — modified to a certain extent all along the course of its " phylogeny," wherever variation occurred. Modified how far ? That is for us a very important question. Do Weismann's newer views admit of use- inheritance in the literal sense ? Or do they only admit of certain changes in the germ plasm, sympa- thetic to vital changes in the parental organism, but not necessarily initiating the same changes in the offspring ? In Romanes' language, does Weismann now accept representative congenital changes ( = true use-inheritance), or only the lower class or classes, nutritive changes ( = Weismann's new theory of the origin of variation), or nutritive and specialised ? l This is a question of importance for us as students of human progress. True use-inheritance, if it occurs, constitutes a possibility of rapid advance in contrast to the painfully circuitous method of natural selection. So far as I am aware Weismann has not spoken on this point. Reluctantly, and as it were casually, he has cancelled the central doctrine of his scheme, that of the absolute continuity and stability of germ plasm. It must be deemed at least possible, accord- 1 Romanes gives as an example of the last : " The fathers have eaten sour grapes, and the children " were born with wry necks ! 2$6 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv ing to Weismann's later views, that use-inheritance should take place. The question will demand more imperiously than ever the eliciting of an answer from facts. Accordingly, when Mr. Benjamin Kidd builds his sociology on the absolute non-inheritance of acquired qualities, he is building on a rock perhaps, but on a rock whose discoverer himself has under- mined it and stored it with explosives. This is not our only objection to Mr. Kidd's premises, but even in itself it is a grave matter. It is possible to postpone as a merely technical point the question, whence come the variations with which natural selection deals ? So long as such vari- ations do arise, it may be said, there is little need to trouble ourselves with the how or the whence. But Weismann's dealing with the question is less vigorous and rigorous than it was. His fairy tale has suffered. As they now stand his doctrines are less astonishing, and somewhat less incredible. There is still one more point to name ; we may call it the second basis of Mr. Kidd's sociology. It is held that where progress ceases you have in its place not stagnation, but actual retrogression. No prog- ress, but by natural selection; nothing but retro- gression, where panmixia prevails. So far as I am aware, Weismann has never recanted this position,1 which has tremendous sociological consequences in Mr. Kidd's hands. Yet it seems a characteristic bit of the newest science, a piece of purely deductive 1 In 1895 ne made the admission that panmixia could not in itself fully account for retrogression, though it tended that way; and the obscure doctrine of germinal selection was brought in as a supplement to panmixia. CHAP, xvin A "FAIRY TALE OF SCIENCE"? 257 reasoning from facts, or from a mixture of facts and theories, and a deduction of doubtful logical cohe- rence. Scientific friends inform me that there is great division of opinion among men of authority1 on the question how panmixia must work out. Will it mean continuous retrogression? Will it reach an average mediocrity and stop there ? Will it mean a divergence into two or more distinct types? Doctors differ. Surely then Mr. Kidd has planted his feet on a second slippery stone. As a matter of obvious prob- abilities one does not see how continuous embodi- ment of the stable germ plasm of to-day should or could mean continuous degeneration and progressive inefficiency. On a first glance, at any rate, that view seems absurd. And the division of opinion among biological experts emboldens one to break away from the dogmatism of Professor Weismann and Mr. Kidd. 1 Professor Baldwin, the psychologist, refuses, for one, to admit Weismann's theory of necessary retrogression. CHAPTER XIX HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY — STRUGGLE MADE ABSOLUTE MR. KIDD Resemblance to Comte — Intenser emphasis on biology [cf. Mr. Platt- Ball] — (i) Panmixia = degeneration is inconsistent with dreams of socialism or of final balance — Selfishness, however, may not care for remote consequences — [Ought Panmixia further to imply extinc- tion?] — Also, social " statics" are blotted out — And evolution be- comes almost identical with progress — Could not Mr. Kidd save many essential positions without this assumption? — (2) Next, if progress implies struggle — And selfish reason makes unwilling to struggle for good of the race, supernatural counterpoise of religion must help, as hitherto — Now, Weismann had riddled his own posi- tion with qualifications — Kidd also appeals to biology by a doctrine of the social organism; but everything here depends on philosophy, not biology — (3) First, the doctrine of reason; reason is formal, as with A. J. Balfour, Darwin, Drummond — For Mr. Kidd also holds that biological law applies without a break to rational man — Yet it disturbs the process of evolution — And Bagehot, Stephen, Drum- mond have noted other changes due to it — Can it be wholly evil? — Balfour and Kidd repudiate Kant or Coleridge's deeper sense of " reason " — But they cannot avoid such sense if it lies in the word and in the fact — (4) Secondly, doctrine of religion as anti-rational — Not = " future judgment"; that is rational! — Can we believe the irrational ? — Does not Kidd tamper with Christian equalitarian- ism? — Biologically; variation may be purposeful and professive — Historically; reason is progressive; by rational methods — Religion its fulfilment — It needs a force to give it motive and constancy THERE is a great deal to recall Comte in Social Evolution. We have a long and interesting appeal 258 CHAP, xix HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY 259 to history. We have the doctrine of altruism assumed, without inquiry or justification, as a definition of the moral ideal; though it is ousted from the place of legitimate authority which Comte gave it by Mr. Kidd's anarchical conception of reason as purely self- ish, and has to borrow its credentials from non- rational religion. Above all we have the appeal to biology more unhesitating than ever.1 " It may be remarked that nothing tends to exhibit more strik- ingly the extent to which the study of our social phe- nomena must in future be based on the biological sciences, than the fact that the technical controversy now being waged by biologists as to the transmission or non-transmission to offspring of qualities acquired during the lifetime of the parent, is one which, if de- cided in the latter sense, must produce the most revo- lutionary effect throughout the whole domain of social and political philosophy."2 Yes, it is striking; most extremely striking; so remarkably striking, indeed, that one would have expected the author to reconsider the question, whether it is necessarily true, if not to raise the question, whether it is even possibly true. Comte himself, phenomenalist to the backbone, while insisting on the connection of sociology with the lower science of biology, insisted also on its separate prov- ince and independent laws. Now it appears that 1 P. 203, towards end of Chap. VII. The same thing is to be noted in Mr. Platt-BalPs little book against use-inheritance (see Preface, p. vii). 2 Mr. Kidd differs from Mr. Sutherland — (i) in appealing to the working of struggle rather than that of elimination among mankind. Neither really succeeds in appealing to the struggle, or to the elimina- tion, implied in true natural selection; (2) Mr. Kidd allows reason to do something — it makes mischief! 260 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv sociology — like one of the colonies of France — is to be merged outright in the mother empire. Every- thing is to be biological. Human wisdom, for the most part, is to be an incidental deduction from the laws of life, as manifested in four-footed beasts and fowls and creeping things of the earth. Is it really the case that the progress of science since Comte makes this conclusion inevitable ? Or is it rather a retrogression in the higher culture — a relapse from the not too lofty philosophical sympathies of Comte — which gives us the proposed biological tyranny ? It is an excellent thing, that each man should be an enthusiast for his own speciality ; assuredly it is an excellent and healthy thing ; but there are limits ! The doctrine of inevitable retrogression when prog- ress ceases — which we noted in the previous chap- ter as Mr. Kidd's second great debt to Weismann — has important consequences for sociology. It sweeps away socialistic dreams, as well as Spencer's doctrine of a stationary state. The second will probably find few mourners to shed a tear over it, though it may be difficult to give up the purely economic conception of a stationary state. What will happen when the world is absolutely too full, and population must cease to grow? That is one of the unrevealed mysteries of Mr. Kidd's credo. Will he tell us the world is not going to last so long ? Will he appeal to a struggle for eminence as doing the work of the old struggle for life ? In the latter case much of his book would need reconsidering. As to socialism, he points out with much force that arguments which show it to be unscientific may yet fail to dislodge it from the minds of men. Sociological science warns the socialists, CHAP, xix HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY 261 " You will retrograde,1 and therefore your posterity will soon be extinguished." Suppose the socialist to reply, " What on earth do I care about posterity ? I mean to have an easy time of it myself ! " Then cer- tainly your remonstrance has missed fire. Another consequence of some importance for socio- logical science attaches to this second great loan of Mr. Kidd's from Weismann. The old Comtist and post-Comtist division into statics and dynamics — con- ditions of order2 and conditions of progress — falls to the ground. Mr. Kidd discusses the " conditions of progress," and these only. The formula seems to be, " Take care of progress and stability will take care of itself ; " a formula which follows directly from Weismann's dilemma — advance or downright retrogression — and yet once more so startling a position that once more it seems Mr. Kidd ought to have been arrested, as by a large type note of interrogation or by a danger signal, and ought to have inquired whether something had not been ignored when biology was transferred wholesale to 1 There are two points here : (i) you will retrograde, because natural selection will cease ; (2) natural selection will extinguish you, because you have retrograded. The second will only hold true if social- ism and stationariness are partial. Like the eight hours' movement, or like bimetallism, socialism (etc.) must seek to come in by international arrangement if it is not to be speedily swamped by competition from hardier races, within which natural selection is still going on. But, if it were an international possibility, the whole world might jog quietly down hill (see p. 315). — That is the theory. Facts do not seem as yet fully to bear it out. France is still a great power, though perhaps in a perilous way (Feb. 1899). And at least France is being swamped by the more prolific races. 2 Comte's Statics, however, as he states them, are rather abstract con- ditions of social well-being than conditions of social order. 262 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv the life and history of man. The young lions of the Radical party will welcome Mr. Kidd's formula with delight ; but one would rather hear what the old lions have to say to it. Yet another consequence may be noted ; evolution, with Weismann and Mr. Kidd, is almost though not altogether equivalent to progress. It is progress wherever it is not downright retrogression. Stagna- tion is impossible, panmixia and retrogression are rare. No doubt panmixia will yield continuous evo- lutionary change while it lasts ; but panmixia is essentially a limited phenomenon ; it is an exception to the general rule. It may prevail in solitary islands, literal or metaphorical ; but the great tides and con- tinents of life are peopled by struggling, suffering, progressive creatures. On a broad view, evolution means progress. Before leaving this assumption, it may be well to ask how much depends upon it ? Go on, or you will go back ; acquiesce in struggle, if you don't wish to retrograde ; that is a very urgent appeal — an over- whelming appeal, one might call it. Yet in many respects the same result might be reached by the narrower and less urgent, yet tolerably effective appeal, acquiesce in struggle if you wish to progress and to avoid stagnation. Few of us would be con- tent with a " stationary state " from the present hour and onwards. The narrower appeal would hold us. The same practical results would be reached, with a less precarious and less vulnerable array of assump- tions. Socialism would still be condemned as arrest- ing the further progress of the species. Evolution and progress might still be regarded as equivalents — • CHAP, xix HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY 263 perhaps more so than ever ; but we could reopen the book of Social Statics, and admit (for those who de- sired it, or who felt bound to anticipate it) visions of an ultimate stationary state. We pass now to Mr. Kidd's first basis, assumed from Weismann, the doctrine that all progress implies struggle and natural selection. This doctrine yields the first or almost the first abstract formula for social dynamics. Comte and others gave us historical sketches and sequences, not general principles or causes of progress.1 What then are the conditions of human progress as formulated by Mr. Kidd ? Primarily they are physiological. Let men fight the battle of life ; they will advance. Easy circumstances, enjoyed in an easy spirit, imply arrest, and perhaps arrest implies retrogression. But the wholesome biological ten- dency to struggle, and struggle on, is interfered with by man's gift of reason. The instincts of race keep the beasts in the path of progress, e.g. by struggling in the interests of their offspring. But many human beings — e.g. the school of Mrs. Mona Caird — resent these struggles as an impertinence and an absurdity. So far, Mr. Kidd agrees with them. It is irrational to acquiesce ! Reason makes us conscious of self ; selfishness therefore and selfishness alone is rational behaviour. But rational behaviour, in this sense of the word, leads straight to retrogression. Now, natural selection would have its slow remedy for this. If the human race had entered the cul-de-sac of selfishness, natural selection would calmly have 1 If Comte had formulated these, they might have found their way into his Statics rather than his Dynamics. 264 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART IV waited till a rational race endowed with higher ten- dencies " happened " to be evolved ; whereupon humanity would quickly have been extinguished in competition with the new race. But fortunately for the prospects of mankind, such an evolution has already " happened." Mankind is a race fitted to survive. Or rather — Mr. Kidd does not write on this point like an ultra-Darwinian, giving the largest possible play to chance, but like one who has a belief in the purposefulness of organic life — the biological laws of human society supply a counterpoise to the dangers introduced by reason. We have reason to make us selfish ; but we have religion to make and keep us altruistic, in despite of our reason. All religions are preter-rational and altruistic, Christianity the most of all. So we have been swayed, and have struggled, and have progressed. We have struggled in war. We have struggled by mere contact, when lower races have melted away at the presence of civilised man. We are struggling to some purpose in the scramble for Africa. And, beyond a doubt, we of the white races shall succeed in a further struggle to control the Yellow Terror for the greater good of humanity. Mr. Charles Pearson's formid- able table, proving the rapid increase of blacks in the United States, is met by another set of tables, prov- ing that the increase is not so rapid after all. Such effect has Christianity had in making us altruistic that we have voluntarily widened the sphere of rights within each nation. Yet we are not drifting into socialism. Quite otherwise ; what the Zeitgeist really means is to secure genuine equality of oppor- tunity— intensified struggle between citizen and CHAP, xix HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY 265 citizen — accelerated progress ! The yielding of Militarism to Industrialism, and the allied change "from status to contract/' are earlier stages in the same great development by which competition grows ever more and more intense. Here then we have Comte's three appeals brought into odd harmony with an apology for supernatural or at least for " ultra-rational " religion. This is to be heartily welcomed as an advance in the right direction ; and the criticisms passed by Mr. Kidd, on the contemptuous treatment of the origin of religion by Mr. Spencer and his underlings, are well deserved and well established. A saner view of history cer- tainly does commend the opinion, so powerfully advocated by Seeley, that religion is the great ani- mating force in states and societies, the master- builder of historic greatness. Nor can it be denied that there was need of reaction from a one-sided intellectualism, which had prevailed even in quarters where we find but little faith in reason.1 Granting all this, and granting it gladly, one must go on to express grave distrust of the process by which Mr. Kidd reaches his conclusion ; of the terms in which he formulates it; and of the affirmations with which it is connected. First, even if we accepted the claim that biology was to be the final judge, we must regard Mr. Kidd's Weismannism as a very insecure foundation. We have already noted in some detail how the denial of use-inheritance had been qualified and weakened and transformed by its author even before Mr. Kidd applied to Weismannism for a social gospel. And 1 E.g. Mill and Buckle. See below, in the closing paragraphs. 266 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv we have seen that the doctrine of necessary regress in the absence of struggle and consequent advance is a precarious deduction from Weismann's own prem- ises, and is scarcely necessary to Mr. Kidd's socio- logical system. Hitherto, however, we have considered only one form of Mr. Kidd's dependence on biology.1 So far, we have spoken of his doctrine concerning men qua physical organisms, exposed to the same conditions as other living creatures. A different use of language by Mr. Kidd must now be considered. His further doctrines regarding reason and religion are brought into connection with biology by means of the familiar phrase, the social organism. True, Mr. Kidd thinks that other writers who have used this phrase have led us very little, if at all, farther on. Still, it points us in the right direction, and the new guide is confident of securing better results. Not man the individual, but society as such, is now viewed as illustrating bio- logical law. There are conditions of vitality or of progress — progress is a manifest fact; there are difficulties revealed by observation or by conscious- ness ; and there are safeguards or remedies discov- ered by analysis. This does not sound very like Darwinism, still less like Weismannism, though it is brought forward as based on the latter. The truth is, the basis here is nothing ; " social organism " is only a phrase ; the analysis here is everything. All depends upon the truth or erroneousness, the worth- 1 Professor Lloyd Morgan shows very tellingly that Mr. Kidd is not warranted by any facts he adduces in contrasting man's intellectual and his moral evolution (Habit and Instinct, p. 345). Yet another part of the case therefore breaks down. CHAP, xix HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY 267 lessness or the value, of Mr. Kidd's doctrines of religion and reason. In dealing with these points, he must speak as a philosopher. His biological know- ledge does nothing here to guard him against error. The doctrine of reason is similar to what we find in Mr. A. J. Balfour's Foundations of Belief. Each writer, in a footnote,1 repudiates any higher or deeper doctrine of reason than that which regards it as a calculating machine or process of inference. This implies that reason is passive in knowledge, and plays no part in determining the motives of human con- duct. The effect of the latter belief, when held by intuitionalists, is that they postulate a moral faculty of conscience alongside of reason and independent of it. In Darwin the effect is this, that moral motives are interpreted by the animal impulses of gregarious creatures, impulses which are held to be extended in range, but not altered in quality, by the advent of reason. And in Drummond the effect is that he looks for one set of impulses which even in animals may be labelled good and right, in contrast to mere self-seeking. Only by such a discovery is Drummond able to save morality. In assuming that biological law may be applied en masse to human conditions, Mr. Kidd seems to reaf- firm the doctrine that reason has no material influence upon motive. Yet it turns out otherwise. He does believe that the animal nature of man is affected by reason, viz. for the worse ! Conscious of what he is doing, man objects to sacrifice himself to his family 1 Social Evolution, p. 73, 2nd edition. Foundations of Belief ^ p. 195. 268 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv or his tribe ; instinct might have led the ape to make the sacrifice automatically. Reason thus tends to make man purely selfish ; and sometimes the ten- dency has its full effect. After all selfishness is the only reasonable behaviour. If indeed reason can be controlled, it promises of great social advance through the superior cleverness which it imparts ; but in itself it is a purely anarchical force. De Maistre or New- man could not have spoken more severely of it. Let us recall here what we have learned from other evolutionists regarding the advent of reason. It has arrested the evolution of the body (Drummond, etc.). It has wrapped mankind round in a mantle of law, custom, and institution, capable of intellectual not physical inheritance (e.g. Mr. L. Stephen). It has largely substituted imitation or conversion for rivalry to the death (Bagehot). And now Mr. Kidd tells us that reason abruptly closes — so far as its influence extends — the process of upward social evolution. Does not all this support the conclusion that reason is something quite different from a mere colourless medium or calculating machine ? One fully agrees with Mr. Kidd that reason checks the automatic work- ing of instinct. Where reason appears, systematic selfishness and sin become possible as they never were before. But unselfishness too becomes possible as it never was before ; it has a new significance. Reason has broken up the unity of the life of sense. Does it do nothing except break it up ? At the low- est, is reason not shrewd enough to perceive the un- happiness of a selfish life, the greater gain to oneself of a life animated by unselfish and far-reaching interests ? CHAP, xix HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY 269 Something must be added here regarding the use of the word reason by Mr. Kidd and Mr. Balfour. Reason is narrowed by them to reasoning, and even {pace Mr. Balfour) to rationalism. Mr. Balfour's footnote seems to be dealing Coleridge a sly hit when it repudiates acquaintance with the Logos. Now no doubt Coleridge had a provoking habit of exclaiming " Logos " as if it were a talisman of magic power. We have seen something similar in our own day on the part of that very able and powerful and now ven- erable Hegelian writer, Dr. Hutchison Stirling. In his case, " the Notion " was the talismanic word. Mr. Kidd again goes straight to Kant,1 by whom, of course, Coleridge was influenced. But Kant is very obscure. Some provocation had then been offered the plain Briton. And the way in which the doc- trine of Reason or Logos shaped itself with Kant or with Coleridge — in many points alike ; in many points, also, not alike — was open to further criticism. Every doctrine of " faculties " is, to a large extent, artificial. Reason and Understanding shade into each other, however we may choose to contrast them. But, just on that account, the plain Englishman will find it hard to keep clear of the deeper and more mystic features of reason. He wants to be a practi- tioner in the simpler branch of the art ; well ! the arts are not two but one. His own words will prove disobedient to him. Words are something more than the clothes of thought : they are its incarnation. We inherit words ; we use them in our service, enno- 1 Without reporting him very accurately. Grave objection might be taken to the formulation of each of the three great Kantian positions given by Mr. Kidd, 2/0 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv bling them or, more frequently, debasing them ; they lived before us, and they will long outlive our very memory. We are the fleeting shadows; they are the substances. Words are like homing pigeons ; they will carry our messages, if we manage them wisely ; but with an instinct surer than our choice — with an instinct not to be overborne by our caprice — they will go there, to that one point where each is at rest. If we take up the great task of the imper- sonal reason of mankind, it is in vain that we express our determination to keep clear of the transcendental or of the logos ! It is in us and we are in it ; in it, or in Him, we live and move and have our being, un- less Mr. Balf our carries us off in his alluring company upon one of his favourite excursions to " a standpoint outside of reason." Inmates of a madhouse are as nearly as possible emancipated from the logos ; to all others the logos is " closer than breathing." Mr. Kidd's doctrine of religion is largely deter- mined by his doctrine of reason. Reason, though useful (like fire) as a servant, is, like fire, a thing an- archical and destructive. Religion, the source of order, is, by the very nature of the case, extra- rational. Religion makes it man's interest or man's impulse to do things which are not personally for his profit, and which reason therefore discourages. At first blush, one is tempted to connect Mr. Kidd's doctrine of religion with the familiar doctrine of future rewards and punishments. These are repre- sented as supernatural motives for doing good. They are not, however, extra-rational ; they make it worth one's while to be moral. Righteousness is strictly CHAP, xix HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY 2/1 a rational and self-interested policy, if this be the truth. This is not therefore Mr. Kidd's meaning ; and the doctrine in itself is unsatisfactory. Selfish- ness produced to infinity remains selfishness still ; it does not turn into righteousness or unselfishness. Other worldliness is only a more morbid growth from the same root as worldliness. If it is moral — if it is one's duty — to preach the doctrine of future judg- ment, that is only because selfish fears and selfish hopes, once awakened, may be transformed, without a visible break, into something nobler than them- selves. They are moral protoplasm (in the true and Aristotelian sense). They are the germ, though only the germ, of goodness. When once, however, we have shut out this in- terpretation of Mr. Kidd's doctrine of religion, it is very hard indeed to say what the doctrine means. Religion works powerfully, but irrationally; that is all we are told. It sounds as if religion were a sort of white magic or hypnotic influence. It sounds like a revival of opinions held by wise men under the Roman Empire, according to Gibbon, when all re- ligions " were considered by the people as equally true, by the philosopher as equally false, and by the magistrate as equally useful" Religion serves the public weal ; religion augments altruism ; the Chris- tian religion in particular attains its ends by a sweeping dogma of human equality. But how Christianity or any other religion captures the wills of human beings, of that we have no explanation. And when we find that Mr. Kidd, in view of the scramble for Africa, and of the taking of the black races under white tute- lage, thinks that Christianity must consent to modify 2/2 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv its equalitarian dogma, a dogma that has been so operative and so useful in the past, one surmises that a high appreciation of the past usefulness of the Christian religion is quite compatible with a very cool and detached consideration of its claim to present authority. Indeed, can any man believe that which by definition is non-rational ? And — to take another point — is not Mr. Kidd's proposed tampering with the rigour of Christianity a most unholy piece of rationalism ? Alas ! The countrymen of Cecil Rhodes seem in small danger of being irrationally altruistic, or democratic, or humanitarian in their treatment of the black man ! And if the premises are true, is not Mr. Kidd's personal counsel most sub- versive and pernicious ? If religion blindly obeyed in the past has made us what we now are, must we not still obey religion with what is called blind fidelity ? If irreligion has brought its penalties hitherto, will not irreligious acts incur the same doom hereafter ? And irreligious theory no less ! Biologically, Mr. Kidd seems to have left one pos- sibility unconsidered. Congenital variations may be due to the environment (by use-inheritance or by dif- ferences of nutrition), or they may be due to amphi- mixis ; or thirdly, they may be due to an inner ten- dency to vary. Mr. Kidd, in his enthusiastic adhe- rence to Weismann, has left the last possibility out of consideration ; yet Romanes points out that Darwin was inclined to look in that direction. Now, if there is a tendency to variation in living species, if variation is not simply forced on them by environment, there is no reason for assuming that variation will be purely CHAP, xix HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY 2/3 casual or non-telic. The embryo is a wise little archi- tect, who builds up a new life out of a speck of proto- plasm by the help of nutritive materials. He makes no mistakes ; he gives us new organisms each after its kind, each perfect in every part, unless where mere force damages his work. If this wise little architect varies his plan slightly, it is far from being obvious that he varies at random. If he knows so much as he plainly does know, should we not give him credit for knowing a little more ? If he knows enough to keep him faithful to the plan of the specific type, ought we not to believe that, when he introduces variations, he knows what he is doing, that he makes improvements, not random shots ? He is not a piece of lifeless mechanism. He is a standing miracle — a " natural supernatural." We are confidently told that the abandonment of belief in preformation and adop- tion of the theory of epigenesis was a heavy blow to teleological and theistic doctrines. I confess I should have thought the opposite. Is there not more of the likeness of miracle in the emergence of an organism, true to its own type, from a speck of living jelly, than in the growth of a detailed miniature by mere accre- tion in bulk ? Be that as it may, there is at any rate no literal preformation, and there is the fulfilment of purpose. Then, if variation occurs spontaneously — from the resident forces of life itself — can variation be a thing of random direction ? Now random variations may become purposeful if they are well weeded by natural selection. But varia- tions which are purposeful from their very beginning — like those due to use-inheritance, if such are really transmitted — do not need to be sifted by the elaborate 2/4 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv and tedious process of natural selection. It is per- fectly conceivable that purposeful variations1 occur spontaneously in each species, and are a direct source of progress. When we leave biology for sociology and the sphere of reason, the possibility spoken of becomes a certainty. Reason tends to continuous advance ; and its achievements are inherited by means of human culture, with its special agency, human or rational speech, passing into higher and more power- ful developments in the form of writing and again of printing. This is recognised in Mr. Leslie Stephen's view of society ; society is an organic tissue, in virtue of the communion which exists between its parts, through reason and through speech as the embodi- ment of reason. The definition of civilisation found in Professor Ritchie's Darwinism and Politics, viz. " the sum of those contrivances which enable human beings to advance independently of [biological] heredity," points us in the right direction. Mr. Kidd has missed the obvious truth because he is too intent on biology, and too hurried in his glance at human society and human reason. " Biologists " may prove if they can "the non-transmission to offspring of qualities acquired during the lifetime of the parent." If biologists make out their case, they prove that such qualities are not transmitted biologically or organically. They cannot possibly show that "the effects of use and education " are not " transmitted by inheritance." Every time a child goes to school, he is entering upon such an inheritance. True, he may 1 Not that we can claim Darwin's authority for this belief. CHAP, xix HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY 275 inherit little "at birth." What of that? Human progress cannot conceivably be regulated by "the accumulation of congenital variations above the aver- age " and by nothing else. That would imply that the world could gain nothing from an intelligent sociologist unless he happened to leave a son who was slightly more effective, socially, than himself. The truth is that genius is rarely or never reproduced in offspring, while yet progress is secured by the human, the rational methods. " The sons " of the wise, as Old Testament language reminds us, are other than his family after the flesh. Even in dying, " he shall see his seed." Shakespeare is Shake- speare, not to one generation merely, but to every age. Newton survives in the senior wranglers of to- day, who could expose so many of his errors, and tell him so many things he never dreamed of. If Mr. Kidd's views are solid, he has contributed directly to human evolution by his very stimulating book; a contribution quite independent of " accumulation of congenital variations"; while if Mr. Kidd is wrong, one may hope to make some small but direct ' contri- bution to human welfare by exposing his fallacies. Really it is almost ludicrous to spend so much time in beating in an open door ! Yet the conclusion pointed to is one of great scope and importance, if we consider it thoughtfully. Far from being a mere accidental accretion upon the evolutionary process, reason has transformed everything. Reason is not formal but constitutive. Reason is not simply a cal- culating machine, but a principle, whose workings are seen both in nature and in man, both in know- ledge and in conduct. It is not selfish but moral 276 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv behaviour that deserves, and alone deserves, to be called rational. And, if our view of reason changes, our view of religion must change with it. Religion is not the contradiction but the fulfilment of reason. For rea- son is immanent in all things. Every one of Mr. A. J. Balfour's parallel pigeon-holes is a simple depart- ment or manifestation of reason. " Ethics " and " ^Esthetic " are as rational as abstract scientific knowledge; how could they arise save in a rational consciousness ? And assuredly religion also must be a superstructure reared on the foundations of reason. But it is not true, as the intellectualists hold, that morals or aesthetics add nothing to that which is pre- sented to us in knowledge. It is not true, as Hegel- ianism seems to imply, that goodness and beauty are mere allotropic forms of rational system, or that logic furnishes the master key to their meaning. Our knowledge is real knowledge, but has its limits ; and the meeting-point of these various stems lies under- ground, well out of sight. To God, their connection may be self-evident, their interdependence manifest ; to man, these great truths must continue largely matter of faith. And therefore we do not speak idly when we say that reason finds its fulfilment not strictly in itself, but above and beyond itself, in religion. Men do not need religion to make it their interest to be good. That is, most deeply, our human interest. Yet man is in bondage. " The good that we approve we per- form not; the evil that we allow not, that we do." By a " pleasureless yielding " to " petty solicitations of circumstance," we destroy ourselves. Deliverance CHAP, xix HYPER-DARWINISM IN SOCIOLOGY comes from above. " What the law could not do, in that it was weak through the flesh," has yet been done, and done in a Diviner way. Here is the true apologetic vindication of religion. Religion is no superfluity, though reason itself — so far as its influ- ence goes — inclines us towards what is good. Re- ligion is the breath of life, the touch of God, making that a reality, strong and victorious, which apart from it would be nothing but a faint aspiration or a bitter and hopeless regret. CHAPTER XX SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS Self-contradictions — Comte is arbitrary — Biology has been reinforced by evolutionary theories, yielding different forms of sociological doc- trine— I. Analogy, without struggle; Stephen — 2. Continuity, without struggle ; Spencer, Alexander (partly) — 3. Analogy of Darwinism; Bagehot, Alexander, Ritchie (?) — 4. Continuity of nat- ural selection; Sutherland, Drummond (?), Kidd — None of these wholly succeed ; old authorities will return ! — Or idealism, which is compatible with the old authorities, may give us a more satisfying doctrine of evolution — What have we been taught? — (i) A social organism exists — Idealism reinforces this lesson — (2) Struggle has been useful; "will it not be? as discussion? as competition? — In light of idealism this seems possible — Of fact, probable — Must not exaggerate its place; it is subordinate in life of reason — [Mallock] — Finally, does progressiveness of evolution make it a guide to con- duct?— Difficulties in biology ; environment constant? — Some forms have stopped ! — Some never started ! — Differentiation plainer here than progress — Reason makes for progress in history — Is it all- sufficient? (Mill, Buckle) — Ancient civilisation failed — Morality and Christianity must safeguard modern civilisation AT the close of our wanderings, we propose to hold a stock-taking of the wisdom which we have picked up by the way. In other words, we shall run rapidly over the suggestions that have been brought before us, and try to estimate their value. We must note once again in how many voices and in how contra- dictory a fashion our teachers speak. Scientific soci- ology is still a hope rather than a fact ; the " ethics 278 CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS of evolution " may mean any one of half-a-dozen or half-a-hundred things. The wisdom proffered to us is hydra-headed, it is million-tongued. But we must also try to decide, in general terms, what positive contribution to human guidance we may reasonably expect from "biological" inquiry. And we must look more closely at the definitions of evolution, especially at the question whether evolution is or is not identical in meaning with progress. I Li- lii Comte, the appeal to biology occupied a limited, almost a subordinate, position. Biology was the science next below sociology; it furnished the soci- ologist with suggestions ; but decisive guidance was found in the wise man's inspection of human phenom- ena, or in his study of past history. We have seen, however, on how many distinct principles, and with how large an infusion of arbitrariness, Comte read off these lessons. In our opinion, such guidance as Comte yields was due to the working in him of the rational and moral nature of man. So far as biology in particular was of service, it gave him only parables. Biology leaped into much greater prominence when the doctrine of organic evolution was propounded, and when evolution was further generalised (however vaguely) as a cosmic process. We distinguish two phases in this appeal — non-Darwinian evolution and Darwinian ; and two forms of each, according as evolution is appealed to for analogies bearing on the social and ethical life of man, or according as an effort is made to merge that social and ethical life in a continuous evolution upon naturalistic lines. 280 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PARTIV First, we have evolution without the assertion of struggle applied to human affairs by way of analogy. This is chiefly exemplified in Mr. Stephen's doctrine of " social tissue," by which he serves himself heir to Comte. The doctrine, however, is without authority. It remains a hypothesis. We may, if we will, regard morals as the laws of social welfare ; Mr. Stephen would add, versus individual welfare. No proof is given that we must do so. Again, part of Professor Alexander's theory falls under this head, viz. the definition of goodness as equilibrium. Here a certain amount of proof is offered us, viz. indirectly, in the form of hostile criticism of rival naturalistic theories; along with which we have Mr. Alexander's assurance that the measure of truth contained in idealistic ethics is in- corporated in his own formula* We see no possible reason to forbid the assertion that goodness is an equilibrium, — it is in the further working out of his views that Mr. Alexander seems to compromise the interests of morality. But we remain unconvinced that " equilibrium " is either the best or the only defi- nition of moral excellence. Secondly, we have evolution — still without vital incorporation of the conception of struggle — in Mr. Herbert Spencer, but now applied not simply by way of " analogy " to the " social organism," but also — and emphatically — to the whole cosmic process,1 society included. At least, that is the effort of Mr. Spencer's philosophy. In its working out, as we 1 If Spencer is biological at all, it is in conceiving the universe itself as an organism. But that organism, by the definition, has no environ- ment! CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS 28 1 noted, it falls short of its aim, giving us rather a sequence of distinct evolutions in different regions. And for the guidance of conduct Mr. Spencer does not keep steadily to the suggestions furnished by cosmic evolution, but varies his standpoints, and sets before us no fewer than three ideals. ">• Thirdly, we have the Darwinian doctrine of struggle ; and we take it for the moment as applied by way of analogy to human relations. Now this Darwinian doctrine is immensely important. True, or false, or half true — and we must not suppose that the truth of evolution, even of organic evolution, stands or falls with Darwinism — Darwinism still remains as when first promulgated, the one dominant theory. It "holds the field." While the factors of Spencer's assumed cosmic evolution are shadowy and vague, the factors of natural selection are — or seem to most minds — plain and undeniable. They may carry us far, or they may carry us only a short dis- tance ; but they are vera causes. Darwinism is applied by Bagehot to nations and to political life generally ; by Professor Alexander to the conflict of ethical ideals. In neither case does the as- sumed evolution follow the lines of true Darwinism. Apart from war, Bagehot recognises imitation (cf. Professor Baldwin) and free discussion as the great factors in progress or change. Both of these are psychical factors ; they make for evolution directly, not indirectly ; they may be expected to move much more quickly than natural selection. Professor Alex- ander again (as we concluded), so far as he makes the conflict of ethical ideals look like a Darwinian struggle, does this by distorting his facts. We may 282 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv add here that his vision of endlessly successive ideals has no authority from Darwinism. In nature, we see clearly that the process of organic evolution has its definite limits, and comes, now on one line and now on another, to a fixed goal. And the assertion that the reigning ideal is the true ideal for its time, though only for its time, finds no justification in the world of nature or in Darwinism. It implies some other philosophy ; and the unknown philosophy does not attract us. Professor Ritchie is hard to group. He tells us that Darwinism applies mutatis mutandis to human things. " How else ? " With such a saving clause one might predicate any attribute of any subject. The stuffed horse of Wallenstein at Prague, with " only the head, legs, and part of the body renewed," is the same horse still, no doubt ; mutatis mutandis. So long as Professor Ritchie does not take a general view of the changes which he recognises, we do not know whether he believes in applying Darwinism by analogy to a higher evolutionary region, or in extend- ing Darwinism to cover the whole field. Perhaps he has never faced that distinction. In any case, his opinions are left too vague to be estimated. He makes no attempt to find guidance for conduct in Darwinism; unless perhaps from its "not sanction- ing " struggle or laissez faire ? Fourthly, however, we have the assertion of Dar- winism as an all-embracing (organic and super- organic) philosophy. This is found in Mr. A. Sutherland, and we are not a little indebted to him for working it out and showing where it leads. It means the denial of the existence of human reason as CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS 283 a factor in the cosmos, and of history as the embodi- ment of human reason. This we might treat as re- ducing the position ad absurdnm. Against such extravagances not metaphysicians only protest, but evolutionists, like Darwin,1 Professor Karl Pearson, Professor Lloyd Morgan. They have shown us in their capacity as men of science how intelligence, as it arises in the animal world, limits, and finally ban- ishes, natural selection. We have further seen that, while faithful to the conception of progress by elimi- nation, Mr. Sutherland does not himself succeed in assuming the kind of elimination implied in true natural selection, viz. starvation or violent slaughter due to struggle. Drummond did not definitely challenge natural selection. Probably he was a believer, and had no intention of excluding its operation from human society. He tried to show, mainly in the brute world, that it had limitations. The argument as he states it seems precarious, inadequate, and, in the light of a better philosophy, unnecessary. We again find pure Darwinism, or rather pure natural selectionism — hyper-Darwinism, a Darwin- ism that goes beyond the master — asserted by Mr. Kidd following the lines of Weismann. We held his physiological basis to be insecure, and his sociological inferences illegitimate, even if it were possible to 1 Darwin's denial of natural selection among the civilised is found in Descent of Man, pp. 143, 618, quoted in Mr. K. Pearson's Chances of Death, etc., i. pp. 127, 128. This may be set against the anti-ethi- cal suggestions of Darwin regarding bee-murder. While he was tempted to interpret the higher by the lower in evolution, he was not pledged to that error. 284 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv treat the problems of morality and sociology in an appendix to biology. But in point of fact Social Evolution turns as much upon the writer's private opinions regarding reason and religion as upon its view of struggle ; * and that view, dissociating struggle from elimination, is not Darwin's view. On the whole, then, this is what we have seen. The one attempt to give authority to biology as a guide for human conduct is the doctrine of evolution. The only accredited theory of naturalistic evolution is natural selection. And it does not, it cannot, apply where reason is at work. When this is more generally recognised we shall see a return of men's minds to the rejected author- ities. Religion, conscience, philosophy, even intui- tionalism, they will all come back, " trooping all together." Probably they will all have contributions to make to the social philosophy of the future. Faith in free will must also return : the ban of ostracism will be cancelled. Denial of freedom is exactly parallel to Mr. Sutherland's denial of reason, though many idealists have mixed themselves up with the one while claiming to be champions of the other. But this is the truth : there is a new factor distinguish- ing spirit from nature; in knowledge it appears as reason, in conduct as will. One is delighted to find Professor Karl Pearson helping, though indirectly and involuntarily, to vindicate libertarianism. 1 Professor Baldwin's Social and Ethical Interpretations furnishes a valuable criticism upon Mr. Kidd. Some of Mr. Baldwin's own posi- tions seem obscure or questionable. But as he decisively subordinates the appeal to biology, he does not form part of the proper field of our present study. CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS 285 Yet all is not done when we recognise the impor- tance of reason and will. We are not at the end of social philosophy. We are only at the begin- ning of a better start. It was intolerable extrava- gance when Mr. Sutherland tried to make away with the existence or distinctive character of mind, though he only blurted out what many had been whispering behind their hands. And yet man has a body as well as a mind ; he has not ceased to be an animal, because he has become a spirit. He is still an organism. Probably old-fashioned ethics and libertarian philosophy made matters too easy for themselves by ignoring everything except the pres- ence of reason and of free well. We must keep both sides in view. May we advance a step farther? May we say that the two sides are not to be contem- plated as two heterogeneous things — soul and body linked together like an ox and an ass yoked in the same team — but as naturally and necessarily related, or perhaps as in some deep sense identical ? This is a programme hard to comprehend and hard to follow, but it has formed part of the noble endeav- ours of idealism. Idealism tells us that " such a being as man is, in such a world as the present," would not be more spiritual without his body. He is spiritual just because he is a human being — human body and human soul. Idealism holds that the animal functions, recognised in the life of man as " hunger and love;' are no more anti-spiritual than spiritual, but rather the raw material of spirituality, of moral goodness, of character; life being the discipline and the ripening of character. It tells us that reason is the fulfilment (as well as the transfer- 286 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv mation) of nature ; that man is the meaning, and there- fore the goal, of the cosmic process which is seen in this world. What lover of humanity, what believer in its Divine goal, would refuse assent to this inter- pretation of man's place in the present world ? Not soul helps flesh more now than flesh helps soul. This is evolutionism, but a very different evolu- tionism from that studied in the previous pages. It would have been impossible therefore to try to bring in " Hegel " as well as " Darwin " in our present study. The new social philosophy, if it follows these lines, may be found to furnish not very much in the way of dogmatic sociology. It may well turn out that, on fuller reflection, the a priori scheme of " all possible societies " will shrink into very small compass, that the general programme formulated by wise teachers will be notably vague. That will not matter greatly. The wise social philosopher will not claim that the one fount of wisdom for men or societies is the fountain which he has enclosed. Ethics proper will be among his data. He will renounce as fraudulent and absurd the attempt to deduce ethics from schemes of physical or even of biological evolution. Have we then learned nothing, it may be asked, from the naturalistic schemes passed in review ? They have contradicted each other (and them- selves) so freely that it seems impossible to maintain they have accomplished much. Nevertheless, we may notice their two chief suggestions. First, it has been suggested that society is an CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS 287 organism ; and Mr. Spencer, with difficulties to face from the materialistic cast of his own philosophy (in its spirit, if not in its letter), suggests that the uni- verse is an organism. These views will receive authoritative support if we accept the idealist evolu- tionism. It will no longer be a mere assertion, it will be part of a great and subtle system of thought, if we now assert that society is an organism ; that its interests are paramount to those of the individ- ual ; that in its good the individual finds his own. Even the bold description of the universe as an organism will be justified. The universe will be revealed on deeper and fuller study as a system, not a chance aggregation of disconnected parts, but a cosmos. Chaos and chance will be banished to the region of bad dreams. Reality will be viewed as the creation and the image of thought. The relation between man and nature will also be conceived as necessary or organic. Everywhere will be traced such a priority of the whole to the parts as organisms display to us. For the true and beau-ideal organism is that which is more than an organism, self-conscious reason. Secondly, we cannot fail to observe a suggestion of a different kind pressed upon us by the study of nature, the suggestion of the importance, nay more, of the indispensableness of struggle. Of course, it is possible, or even probable, that the doctrine of natural selection is not the whole truth, even in the region of biology. Therefore it may be the case that the evolutionary study of nature, as conducted by our scientific leaders, hands on to sociology a stronger recommendation in favour of 288 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv struggle than facts really warrant. Further, we have agreed decidedly to repel the suggestion that natural selection strictly so-called has an appreci- able effect in civilised society, or can account for ad- vances in human morality. Still, unless we utterly reject natural selection — perhaps one might even say, unless we close our eyes to manifest facts — we must admit that struggle exists in nature. And it will need clear proof if we are to believe that the same necessity does not hold in human life. Bagehot and Professor Alexander have mainly dwelt on the importance of free discussion. That is a kind of competition. It is very different, of course, from natural selection. It implies reason and speech and the possible wide diffusion of suc- cessful opinions, — a whole world of causes making for rapid advance in contrast to the heart-breaking tardiness of natural selection. Still, it is a form of struggle. And while defeat here points towards conversion rather than towards extinction, it would be absurd to say that defeat in argument is always painless. It is painful ! And it does not always make for progress. We have ceased to believe as confidently as the men of last generation in the immediate victory of truth.1 Yet if free discussion is maintained it will bring us in time to the ulti- mate victory of truth; we still believe that. And we have learned too that the refusal to give un- bounded sway to argument is not wholly bad. It is not pure perversity. It is partly due to the 1 There are interesting remarks on the evolution of beliefs in Dr. F. B. Jevons's Introduction to the History of Religion at the beginning of chap. xxvi. CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS 289 working of deep but only half-articulate convic- tions and instincts. Men cannot answer the glib logician, but they are sure there is something upon their side of the case to which he has failed to do justice. Socially and morally it would be no ad- vance if mankind laid aside their conservative mis- givings, and sought to set up an age of reason, with all the schoolboy enthusiasm of the Jacobins. Convictions which are more slowly reached are more deeply grounded. Mr. Kidd lays stress upon the sort of competition noted in political economy, personal competition be- tween man and man. Unquestionably this has been a vast historical influence. It had its limits. Cus- tom, as economists since J. S. Mill have taught, very widely forestalled competition in the history of human trade. But the two factors are not neces- sarily inconsistent. They may co-operate, as when custom fixes the amount of a fee, while competition settles who shall do most business and carry off most fees. In that way, or in some fuller way, competition is likely to assert itself irresistibly as the pressure intensifies. Struggle ensures the maxi- mum product. But we have not done with custom when we have recognised the increasing power of competi- tion. In other ways social custom has conditioned the working of competition, notably in the class standard of comfort. Men have never competed en masse for the necessaries of life, or for the chance of piling up a fortune by miserliness. Both per- sonal inclination and social pressure have con- strained those who rise in the world to modify 2QO FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv their scale of expenses. Therefore the foolish pros- perous man will tell the artizan that though richer he is no better off — not a bit — always on the wrong side of the account; and what to do with the boys — ! A distribution of society into separate compartments tends thus to intensify struggle and to increase the total output. The very fact that biology offers social science this second suggestion, in favour of struggle, shows in a crucial instance the unreliableness and self-contradic- toriness of the biological lawgiving. If society is an organism, man ought to live for the general good. If struggle for existence is the true law of moral and social advance, then it is our duty to fight "for our own hands " with all our might. Which view is authoritative? Both cannot be; yet both are "the teaching of biology." It may seem that any attempt to make room for struggle is equally inconsistent with that higher evolutionism based on reason, to which we have pointed. If reason promulgates a doctrine of the social organism, must not reason too feel nonplussed by the assertion that nature teaches the necessity of struggle ? Yet, at the least, the philosopher's study of reason has prepared him to hear of an intenser struggle where conscious life prevails. He sees how self-consciousness draws a more definite line round the individual, making each organism a universe in itself, a microcosm, as no irrational creature is or could be. He perceives that the requirement some- times addressed to man is foolishness — that he should behave as a mere part in a larger social organism. It is idle to talk of such things. Self-consciousness puts CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS 29 1 an end to acquiescence in the mere suppression of the individual. But, if the first and lowest work of reason is to break up the unity of sense, that unity may and must be rebuilt in a higher fashion by the agencies of morality and religion. So far we are willing to agree with Mr. Kidd. Only we do not believe that the first work of reason is its only work. We cannot admit that morality and religion are divorced from reason. Still, if it be true, as wise men taught long before Darwin or Adam Smith, that life is a battle — if it be true, as we have read in an old book, that the life of a Christian man is a " fight of faith " — then we may well expect to find conflict and struggle appearing as elements in the orderliness and beneficence of the social organism. Not indeed such struggle as is found in natural selection ; and very possibly not the " cut-throat competition," as it is called, of unbridled individualism, though in modern commerce we cut prices, not throats, and nothing whatever is gained by ignoring the advance which that fact implies. Not every form of struggle, then, yet some form, and that a keen one, is to be expected and desired. Morality still leaves the individual personally responsible. He must lead his own life, fight his own battle, gain his own prize. And if, in the physical world, natural selection has indeed been at work, — if, so far as it has been at work, its cruel or seeming cruel methods have secured this notable result, a teeming population of healthy, vigorous creatures, fit in every fibre, fit or fittest on all the varied lines along which evolution has reached, — then may it not be that social struggle, acting in union doubtless with other forces, will give us an effective and vigorous and truly happy 2Q2 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv human society? A man, or a school, or a world is the better of hard work. And the world will be kept hard at work ; there is no throwing off the yoke ex- cept for that unhappy minority, the idle classes. Could we destroy social pressure we might find that we had simply destroyed the atmosphere which our souls breathe. Yet, if we admit the permanence of struggle, we must strictly cross-examine the theories which are built on that fact, lest they exaggerate it. They have called the process natural selection, in some cases, perhaps, because they were enamoured of struggle, and love-blinded to its dangers ; in some cases, but hardly in all cases. What can be the reason why Darwinism has had so great a charm for many sociologists and moralists ? Perhaps the reason was that natural selection stated a method of progress without conscious known super- intendence. Many different forces struggled or com- peted — nature selected*; environment selected ; the struggle itself selected. Many different patterns were aimed at ; one pattern resulted, and no one had aimed at it. Such at least is the suggestion underlying Mr. W. H. Mallock's definition of evolution as "the reasonable sequence of the unintended." 1 1 Aristocracy and Evolution, p. 97. I merely observe how curiously the teleological suggestion recurs, even in a phrase which seems de- signed to exclude teleology. Mr. Mallock's interesting book marks an advance, in so far as he insists that progress due to " great men " is more rapid than the physio- logical progress due to natural selection. But he goes on to distin- guish this advance, in the sphere of reason and realm of history, from mere biological evolution, on the ground that in the latter, wholes com- pete, while, in reason and history, parts of the social organism compete CHAP. XX SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS 293 But, if this be the meaning of the appeal to natural selection and to struggle, it almost forces us to ask whether our definition has gone deep enough. Are the competitors in reality so many distinct ultimate factors in progress ? Or are they all held in the grasp of one great evolving system ? not, however, to be defined as matter and motion growing more complex ! Is the relation between the different forces simply or mainly one of rivalry ; is it not predominantly one of co-operation? Is history a Kilkenny cat struggle between nations, or in history is struggle itself subor- dinated to an evolution of mankind ? Ought an en- lightened nation to regard its neighbours mainly as rivals, or mainly as brothers in the common tasks of civilisation ? And so with ethical conceptions ; is the history of moral thought mainly a struggle of system against system, of ideal against ideal, or is it an evolu- tion of one ideal ? And is each moralist pledged by fidelity to his own views to eat up and destroy his rivals, or may he also be the conscious servant of a wider truth? Even in nature, one more and more questions the adequacy of the view which regards the various organisms simply as each other's rivals, the co-operating forces simply as happening to coincide. And, when we pass on to the fuller " symbiosis " of reason and morality, the Darwinian formulae snap in against each other. That does not seem to hit the true line of differ- ence, or to mark the real ground of the failure of biological sociology in the past, which Mr. Mallock once again deplores. " Struggling parts " are not unknown in biological speculation. Psychical progress, by great men or otherwise, is direct and therefore rapid. Mr. Mallock overdoes his apotheosis of competition. We will still believe that even the " great man " may rise to higher things than an exceptional hugeness of desire. 294 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv two. Men superficially regarded are competitors, but essentially they are their brothers' keepers, and mem- bers of one great fellowship. Yet one more attempt may be made to find a guide for conduct in phenomenal knowledge, if evolution everywhere and necessarily is equivalent to progress. We have met this view before — more than once ; first in the appeal to history, then in Mr. Spencer's cosmic doctrine of evolution. Here too, if anywhere, the contendings of Mr. C. W. Williams1 are relevant. Though it offers very little guidance in detail, yet this assertion demands to be looked at. It can be held, and is, apart from any claim to knowledge of the factors of evolution. We do not attempt to say anything further regard- ing merely physical evolution. In spite of Mr. Spen- cer, we doubt the possibility of laying down laws a priori for that process. But we must consider, in the first place, biological evolution, or the evolution of species. And secondly, we shall pass on to speak of evolution in human history. If we might assume natural selection to be the key to organic evolution, we should have a good deal of reason for identifying evolution with progress. " Nat- ural selection " seems to imply the transforming of minute random variations into definite serviceable changes. If everywhere there is movement, the movement ought everywhere to result in progressive efficiency or adaptedness. Yet the assertion is a dif- ficult one. First of all, there is one very plain condition, which 1 Review of the Systems of Ethics founded on Evolution. CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS presumably no critic will question, but which ought to be made explicit. If evolution is to mean progress, it must at least imply continuous adjustment to a constant environment. If the environment changes, if there is no continuity in the definition of " fitness," there can be no real progress. Dissatisfied with my dwelling, I build myself a house exactly suited to my personal needs. That is a real improvement. But forthwith I have to accept an appointment in a dif- ferent town, and must sell my new house at a loss for whatever it will fetch. The improvement due to building for myself is forfeited, and turns to the opposite. Now in the far-off past our planet is said to have passed through more than one ice age. Of course so tremendous a change in environmental conditions involved the forfeiting of past progress. The tests were all (however gradually) altered. The last became first and the first last. The unfit were now found fit, while the fit proved unfit. Physiologi- cal capital was fatally depreciated, like machinery thrown out of use by a better invention. Only here there was no better invention. There was no con- tinuous progress. There was discontinuity and a change of conditions. Evolution then will scarcely mean progress unless first it is continuous evolution. But continuity in evolution of species implies con- stancy of environment. No doubt, speaking broadly, we have had such continuity on the earth for a good many aeons. Secondly, a difficulty occurs as to those species which seem unchanged from remote geological times. Drummond's Ascent of Man has been the one of our authorities which has told us most about these. 296 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv There are shells, it seems, absolutely unchanged through many ages, because they had "arrived." They had reached the limit of possible development on the line which they had chosen. More important still is the case of man, whose physiological improve- ment, according to Fiske, has been superseded and arrested by the emergence of reason, and whose cra- nial development, according to Professor Cleland, has gone about as far as is possible under the laws of space in their bearing on the constitution of the human body. We cannot therefore say — in spite of all Darwinising moralists — that " everything is in flux," moving "from change to change eternally." Evolution seems to be a definitely limited movement, exhausting its possibilities, now in one direction, now in another, now in some low forms of organised life and again in the highest. Further, was this evolu- tion exactly identical with progress even while it lasted ? In the case of man, we shall assume that it was ; was it equally so in the case of the shells ? Progress means, advance on one line ; evolution seems to mean, radiation in many directions. It may be taken then as meaning, differentiation ; or the gradual filling out, by mechanical process, of a de- signed and purposed scheme ; or the eliciting of all the possibilities latent in " protoplasm " at the first. Of these conflicting interpretations the first might suggest Spencer ; the second, a Christian teleology ; the third, Spinozistic Pantheism. There seems no doubt that origin of species by natural selection would imply variation, or differ- entiation of race from race. Animal A preys upon animal B, and threatens to exterminate it. Several CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS 297 specimens of B may deal with the difficulty in several distinct fashions. The swift B will run away from A and make its escape. The cunning B will hide itself from A and elude notice. The strong B will stand up to A manfully, and, after a few struggles, will teach A to seek his prey by preference among less warlike creatures. There is no one means of survival in the struggle ; there are several. At any time, for any species, there are innumerable possible advantages. Candidates for nature's examination can and do spe- cialise. It seems therefore that fitnesses are pro- duced, but fitnesses of manifold types. Progressive improvement (given constancy of environment) every- where results, but it results upon different lines, and the clearest outcome of the process is the transition from the monotony of a few types to an almost infi- nite variety. Of course we must remember that variation in other types constitutes a change in the " environment " of any one type, whether the altered neighbour was a former competitor, or a former ally, or liable formerly to be preyed upon, or making prey formerly of the type in question. It follows that a constant environment, such as "progress" involves, can only be affirmed in a relative and limited sense. And therefore we must similarly qualify the con- nected assertion of continuous organic advance and improvement as the result of natural selection. A third difficulty strikes one in connection with the lowest organisms. Certain shells or the human physique have ceased progressing because they have reached the allotted goal ; good, but why have the lowest not moved up ? Experimental science refuses to admit abiogenesis. Wherever life came from at 298 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv first, it does not now arise from a rearrangement of dead matter. If " all were in motion," including the initiation de novo of life, then we should see through the difficulty. Infusorians would be infusorians — only that and nothing more — because they had not had time to climb up the ladder. But apparently, in point of fact, they have had just as much time as the cedars of Lebanon or the crowning race of man ; and in that time, of course, a vastly greater number of generations. Then why are they still mere common infusorians ? Take it either way ; why have they not progressed out of that state of being ; or, at any rate, why have they not varied ? Through billions on billions of generations — to put it modestly — they have been competing against each other and against the cruelty of environment. Why are they still no fitter ? or, if they are fit enough to survive — -why has any other organism taken the trouble to build up new and higher forms of life? There seems reason to think that this consideration points to some grave flaw or gap in naturalistic theo- ries of evolution.1 On the whole, from our human point of view, we consider that the evolution of species has been at- tended with progress, because " higher " animals and plants have appeared, and, above all, because man has emerged. We must also admit that the evolutionary 1 Mr. A. R. Wallace suggests that the lower types fill up the few places of that kind which nature allots ! Mr. Wallace is a little in- clined to switch on and off selective struggle at his arbitrary pleasure and convenience. His own position is exceptional (see p. 228) ; but, on the naturalistic view, ought not the lowest forms to be originating before our eyes? CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS 299 process has been attended with a vast differentiation of life into forms not all of them admirable from an aesthetic or from a guasi-moral point of view. Whether there is advance upon each divergent line, as differen- tiation takes place, may appear doubtful, though the theory seems to affirm it. Differentiation appears to be proclaimed far more clearly than progress, alike by the theory of natural selection and by the phe- nomena of living but irrational nature. When we turn to human evolution, we find at once that there are changes. The law of differentiation has still been at work, though its conditions are ob- scure and ill-comprehended. We have negroes, Es- quimaux, Mongols, Caucasians, all probably of the same stock, all very dissimilar. Yet even here there is something quite different from animal evolution. Races of men do not dwell simply side by side, indif- ferent to each other, as plant and animal races do. You may, of course have a society built in separate compartments, as in the institution of caste, or in the simpler and more familiar case of slavery. Yet this differentiation, gross and excessive as it is, belongs to another region of things from animal differentiation. The many castes — or the slaves and the oppressors — constitute together one society. The potential unity of the race, implied in reason, has already that notable consequence. Accordingly, the marked physi- ological differentiation of the various races of man- kind does not seem to have taken place in a society having relations even of neighbourhood between its several parts. It has been guessed that race differen- tiation was due to natural selection in different regions 300 FROM COMTE TO BENJAMIN KIDD PART iv of the world, those naturally superior to cold surviving within the Arctic circle, and those who enjoyed im- munity from fever surviving in the tropics. At any rate, the differentiating process came first. While man was mainly an animal — or (what is nearly the same thing) while men were divided from their fellows by geographical barriers — they diverged physiologi- cally ; and no doubt they also diverged socially. But, as soon as reason began to assert itself and make its way, the tendency to differentiation was held in check by a tendency to unity — a growing unity of culture and custom pointing to an ultimate far-off unity of the whole race. The different branches of the human stock can borrow from each other as kindred tribes of animals cannot do. Even if, for a time, the aristo- cratic few have no mind to help the ignorant many, yet the ignorant many are eager to copy the envied few. Simple survival of the fittest and neglect of the unfit is never long the rule in human affairs. Level- ling up is one of the earliest manifestations of reason, when set free to do its work. In the first instance, as between different societies, this process no doubt takes place through war. The stronger race conquers, and the defeated race eagerly imitates the conquerors. This would be fatal to prog- ress if an inferior race were capable of mastering higher races on the field of battle. But, as Bagehot has forcibly pointed out, up to a certain distance the opposite is true ; through many ages, we may be sure that the best man or best race will win at the game of war. Yet how different are the consequences from those of a merely animal victory ! Instead of stub- bornly clinging to their old ways, the conquered CHAP, xx SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS 3