LEIBNIZ THE MONADOLOGY AND OTHER PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS TRANSLATED WITH INTRODUCTION AND NOTES Y ROBERT LATTA, M.A., D.PHIL. (EDIN.) LECTURER IN LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS AT THE UNIVERSITY OF ST. ANDREWS AT THE CLARENDON PRESS 1898 PRINTED AT THE CLARENDON PRESS BY HORACE HART, M.A. PRINTER TO THE UNIVERSITY PREFACE IN this country Leibniz has received less attention than any other of the great philosophers. Mr. Merz has given, in a small volume, a general outline of Leibniz's thought and work, Professor Sorley has written for the Encyclopaedia Britannica a remark- ably clear, but brief, account of his philosophy, and there are American translations of the Nouveaux Essais and of some of his philosophical papers. That is very nearly the whole of English writing about him. Yet few philosophical systems stand so much in need of exposition as that of Leibniz. His theories have to be extracted from seven large volumes of correspondence, criticism, magazine articles, and other discursive writings, and it is only in recent years that this material has been made fully available by the publication of Gerhardt's edition. No complete and detailed account of Leibniz's philosophy has hitherto been published in English, and accordingly I have written a very full Introduction to this book, with illustrative foot-notes, consisting mainly of transla- tions from Leibniz himself. The endeavour of the book is to make the Monadology clear to students. I cannot agree with Dillmann in treating it as of little importance. A 3 VI PREFACE Leibniz himself expressly intended it to be a com- pact and ordered statement of the views he had expounded in many scattered papers and in his somewhat desultory The'odicee, the only book he published. There is evidence of this in his corre- spondence and in the fact that he annotated the Monadology with references to passages in the Tkeodicee. My original intention was to publish a translation of these passages along with the Monadology, but on re-consideration it seemed better to translate several short papers illustrating different parts of Leibniz's system and explaining its growth. Thus the Monadology, as being the centre of the book, is printed first of the translations (although in date it is last), while the other writings follow in chronological order. The only disadvantage of this arrangement is that it places the Principles of Nature and of Grace, which is most akin to the Monadology, farthest away from it. If I might venture to suggest to the student the way in which the book should be read, I would recommend him first to read Part I of the Intro- duction, then the Monadology (without the notes), afterwards Parts II and III of the Introduction, the Monadology again (with the notes), the other translations, and finally Part IV of the Introduction, in which I have endeavoured to ' place ' the philosophy of Leibniz in relation to the systems which came before and after his. My indebtedness to authors is so great and varied that I cannot acknowledge it in detail; but I may mention as specially helpful to me the works of Boutroux, Dillmann, Nourisson, Nolen, and Stein. My thanks are due to Professor Jones, of Glasgow, PREFACE Vll who read the Introduction in manuscript, for much valuable suggestion and criticism; and I am more than grateful to Professor Ritchie, of St. Andrews, who read the whole book, both in manuscript and in proof, and to whom it owes numerous improvements as well in form as in matter. I have adopted the spelling 'Leibniz' in place of the traditional 'Leibnitz,' because the former was invariably used by Leibniz in signing his own name. It ought perhaps also to be mentioned that Parts II and III of the Introduction were accepted by the University of Edinburgh as a thesis for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. ROBERT LATTA. UNIVERSITY OF ST. ANDREWS, June, 1898. TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE PREFACE . . . . . '• v INTRODUCTION : Part I. Life and Works of Leibniz i „ II. General Principles of the Philosophy of Leibniz 21 „ III. Detailed Statement of the Philosophy of Leibniz ....... 74 A. Leibniz's Mathematics in relation to his Philosophy . . . . . 74 B. Matter . 86 C. Organism 108 D. Self-Consciousness ..... i2q Theory of Knowledge . . . .121 Ethics . . . ' . . . .137 „ IV. Historical and Critical Estimate of the Phi- losophy of Leibniz . . . .151 APPENDIX A. Explanation of the Pre-established Harmony 200 „ B. Formation of the Idea of Space . . 202 „ C. Meaning of Cause . . . . . 204 „ D. Leibniz's Logic ..... 206 „ E. Kant on his relation to Leibniz . . 208 THE MONADOLOGY 215 APPENDIX F. Leibniz and Bayle on the multiplicity in the Monad 272 G. Proof of the Existence of God . . 274 ON THE NOTIONS OF RIGHT AND JUSTICE . . . 281 X CONTENTS PAGE NEW SYSTEM OF THE NATURE OF SUBSTANCES AND OF THE COMMUNICATION BETWEEN THEM . . . 297 EXPLANATION OF THE NEW SYSTEM . . . . 319 APPENDIX H. On the Elements of Extension . . 329 THIRD EXPLANATION OF THE NEW SYSTEM . . . 331 )N THE ULTIMATE ORIGINATION OF THINGS . . . 337 APPENDIX I. Growth of Leibniz's Theories regarding Force and Motion . . . '.351 NEW ESSAYS ON THE HUMAN UNDERSTANDING— Intro- duction . ' • . 355 — PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND OF GRACE . : . . 405 INDEX «• . ' - . . 425 ABBKEVIATIONS E. God. Guil. Leibnitii opera philosophical quae extant latina, gallica, ger~ manica omnia, ed. J. E. Erdmann. Berlin, 1840. G. Die philosophischen Schriften von G. W. Leibniz, herausgegeben von C. J. Gerhardt. Berlin, 1875-90. G. Math. Leibnizens mathematische Schriften, herausgegeben von C. J. Gerhardt. Berlin and Halle, 1850-63. Dutens. G. G. Leibnitii opera omnia, nunc primum collecta, studio Ludovici Dutens. Geneva, 1768. Klopp. Die Werke von Leibniz, herausgegeben von Onno Klopp. Hanover, 1864-77. Foucher de Careil. (Euvres de Leibniz, publiees pour la premiere fois d'apres les manuscrits originaux, par A. Foucher de Careil. Paris, 1859-75. Mollat. Rechtsphilosophisches aus Leibnizens ungedruckten Schriften, von Dr. Georg Mollat. Leipzig, 1885. INTRODUCTION PAKT I. THE LIFE AND WORKS OF LEIBNIZ. His Boyhood. ON June 21, 1646, two years before the close of the Thirty Years' War, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz was born at Leipzig. His family was of Bohemian origin ; but his ancestors for several generations had lived in Saxony and Prussia, and his father was a Professor of Philosophy in the University of Leipzig. Leibniz was only six years of age when his father died ; and, though in his early years he had the training of a pious mother, she also passed away before he had completed his Univer- sity studies. The boys of Leipzig in Leibniz's time appear to have been brought up on ' the picture-book of Comenius and the little Catechism ' (Luther's) ; but the soul of Leibniz already sought stronger meat, and having found in the house an illustrated copy of Livy, of which he could not thoroughly understand a single line, he managed to get a tolerable idea of its contents, supple- menting his scanty Latin by a study of the pictures and some judicious guessing. As an indirect result of this precocity, his father's library was thrown open to him, and he wandered at will from volume to volume, finding (as was ever characteristic of him) some good in all1. 1 ' It is characteristic of me to hold opposition (Widerlegeri) as of B 2 INTKODUCTION Providence or Fortune seemed to say to him, Tolle, lege ; and it is significant for the philosophy to come that he turned first to the Ancients, to Cicero, Quintilian, Seneca, Pliny, Herodotus. Xenophon, Plato, the historians of the Roman Empire, and the Fathers of the Church. Of these he tells us that * he understood at first nothing, then gradually something, and finally enough'; but uncon- sciously his mind was coloured by their style and thought, ' as men walking in the sun have their faces browned without knowing it,' and under their inspiration he made it the rule of his life ever to seek clearness in speaking and a useful purpose in acting (in verbis daritas, in rebus usus). Thus at fourteen years of age he was counted by his fellows a prodigy of learning and ability, and already his reading of Logic and intense determination towards clearness of thought and speech had led him to ideas which were afterwards developed into the suggestion of a logical Calculus and an 'Alphabet of Concepts' as means to the discovery of truth 1. University Life. At fifteen years of age Leibniz became a student at the University of Leipzig, and about the same time he became little account, exposition (Darlegen) as of much account, and when a new book comes into my hands I look for what I can learn from it, not for what I can criticize in it.' Schreiben an G. Wagner (1696) (E. 425 b; G. vii. 526). 1 ' Before I reached the school-class in which Logic was taught, I was deep in the historians and poets ; for I had begun to read the historians almost as soon as I was able to read at all, and in verse I found great pleasure and ease ; but as soon as I began to learn Logic I found myself greatly excited by the division and order of thoughts which I perceived therein. I immediately began to notice, so far as a boy of thirteen could, that there must be a great deal in it. I took the greatest pleasure in the Predicaments ' (i. e. the Categories) ' which came before me as a muster-roll of all the things in the world, and I turned to "Logics" of all sorts to find the best and most detailed form of this list. I often asked myself and my schoolfellows to which Predicament and also to which sub-class this or that thing might belong/ Schreiben an (?. Wagner (E. 420 a ; G. vii. 516). LIFE AND WORKS 3 acquainted with the works of some of the modern philo- sophers, beginning with Bacon's De Augmentis Scientiarum. At this time also, as he himself tells us, he read with interest the works of Cardan and Campanella and the suggestions of a better philosophy in Kepler, Galileo, and Descartes. But he was no l read ing-machine, all wound up and going/ He thought for himself : he read in order to ' weigh and consider. ' And thus in after-years he re- calls how, when he was fifteen years of age, he walked alone in a wood near Leipzig, called the Rosenthal, to consider whether or not he should retain in his philo- sophy the 'Substantial Forms' of the Scholastics1. Although his favourite teacher at Leipzig was Jacob Thomasius, a Professor of Philosophy, deeply versed in ancient and scholastic learning, the private reading of Leibniz at first prevailed in his thought and he turned from the older philosophies to * mechanism ' and mathe- matics. The ' Substantial Forms * were for the time set aside, to reappear, transmuted, in later years. His scholastic studies, however, bore fruit in the earliest of his published writings, a graduation thesis with the significant title De principle individui, in which he de- fended the Nominalist position. Intending to devote him- self to the profession of law, he went for a year (in 1663) to Jena, where the mathematician, Erhard Weigel, was lecturing on 'the Law of Nature,' or what we should now call Jurisprudence in general. Doubtless the influence of Weigel tended to confirm Leibniz's mathematical bent, and he still continued his study of history. In 1666 the University of Leipzig, ostensibly on the ground of his youth, refused to give him the Doctorate in Law ; but his thesis, De casibus perplexis in jure, was immediately accepted by the University of Altdorf (near Niirnberg), where he declined the offer of a professorship. Thus ended his connexion with Leipzig. 1 Lettre a M. Remond (1714) (E. 7028 ; G. iii. 606). B 2 4 INTRODUCTION Boineburg and the Elector of Mainz. In Niirnberg, at that time the capital of a small republic, which had suffered less than many other German States from the Thirty Years' War, Leibniz spent a year, in the course of which his extensive curiosity led him to become a member of a secret society of the Rosicrucians, who were trying to find the philosopher's stone. Fontenelle tells us that Leibniz's method of gaining admission to the society was to collect from books on alchemy all the most obscure phrases he could find and to make of them an unintelligible letter, which he produced as evidence of his fitness for membership. The society was so impressed that it immediately ap- pointed him to be its secretary. The chief gain to Leibniz appears to have been that through this society he became acquainted with Baron von Boineburg, ' one of the most celebrated diplomatists of his age/ who had formerly been minister to the Elector and Archbishop of Mainz, the most powerful man in the Empire. With Boineburg Leibniz went to Frankfort, where he wrote and pub- lished a paper on legal education, which was the means of introducing him to the archbishop, in whose service he remained for some time. This was the beginning of his career as a diplomatist. The long war had left Germany in ruins, and, ere there was time to rebuild, the whole empire was threatened by the immense power of Louis XIV, who was dreaming of world-wide sway. The Elector of Mainz, says Leibniz, 'had seen the miseries of Germany, whose ruins were still smoking : he was one of those who had laboured most to bring back rest to the land, from which life seemed almost to have gone. The country was (as one might hardly say) " peopled " with little children, and if war were to break out again (as might be expected when Sweden was irritated and France threatening) there was every reason to fear that this seed of a new population would be destroyed and a great part LIFE AND WOEKS 5 of poor Germany left almost without inhabitant V The treaty of Westphalia had secured peace and some measure of political unity, but it pointed also to an ecclesiastical reunion, yet to be realized, which to men like the Elector of Mainz and Boineburg seemed the best means of re- storing power and happiness to the country. Negotiations for the reunion of Eoman Catholics and Protestants had already been begun, and thus early in his diplomatic career Leibniz took part in the work of conciliation which in various ways he continued throughout his life. At the suggestion of Boineburg he made a special study of the doctrine of transubstantiation, with the result (expressed in a letter to Arnauld in 1671) that he found it impossible to reconcile the Cartesian view of material substance as pure extension either with the Roman Catholic or with the Lutheran doctrine. He accord- ingly formed the purpose of discovering a theory of substance which should satisfy both, and should thus become a philosophical basis for the reconciliation of the Churches. Paris and London. Presently events occurred which led him away from Mainz and gave him new opportunities of study and of intercourse with learned men. Leibniz and his friends felt strongly the necessity of drawing into safe channels the military ambitions of Louis XIV, and accordingly Leibniz prepared a most elaborate work in which he suggested to the King of France the advantages that would arise from a conquest of Egypt, and tried to con- vince him that it was more worthy of a Christian king to fight the unchristian Turks than to harass a poor little people like the Dutch2. This book was never 1 From a letter of Leibniz, quoted by Foucher de Careil, vol. iv. Introduction, p. xx. 2 This Projet de Conquete de I'figypte was published by Foucher de Careil, vol. v. It shows a most remarkable knowledge regarding the state of the country and its possibilities, and so clever are the 6 INTRODUCTION actually presented to King Louis, but Leibniz in 1672 went by invitation to Paris to explain his project. His advice was not taken ; but he remained in Paris for four years, during which he devoted himself to the study of the higher mathematics l and to the discussion of the Cartesian philosophy. He had already corresponded with Arnauld, and he now met also Huygens and Male- branche. At this time, says Leibniz himself, 'law and history were my forte V But intercourse with Huygens and the study of the mathematical works of Pascal intro- duced him to the problems of modern mathematics. Huygens, he tells us3, 'had no taste for metaphysics,' but Leibniz learned from him mathematical methods and principles which influenced the growth of his philo- sophy, and which set him on the way to the discovery of the Differential Calculus. At this time also Leibniz in- vented a calculating machine, superior to that of Pascal, which could only add and subtract, while his own machine could also multiply, divide, and extract roots. And in other ways the residence of Leibniz in Paris greatly affected his life-work. For instance, it probably led to his writing so much in French. He had already, in his essay on the philosophical style of Nizolius (1670), advo- cated the use of the German language for philosophical and other works. But in the time of Louis XIV Paris was the intellectual centre of Europe, and to write for the world was to write in French. While, therefore, plans which it suggests that Napoleon was at one time supposed to have borrowed its ideas for his campaign. Though this has been shown to be a mistake, the coincidence between the suggested expedition of Louis XIV and the actual expedition of Napoleon is sufficiently noteworthy. 1 * The merit of an author in mathematics cannot be disputed, as it can in other subjects. This is the reason why I remained some time in France, in order to perfect myself .in mathematics, and I gave my time to these sciences not on their own account, but in order to make them contribute to the advancement of piety.' Lettre au Due Jean Frederic (undated) (Klopp, iv. 450). 2 Lettre a la Comtesse de Kilmansegg (1716) (Dutens, iii. 456). * E. 702 b ; G. iii. 607. LIFE AND WORKS 7 Leibniz has rightly been called 'the father of German philosophy,' he is only to a very small extent a German author. The four years' residence of Leibniz in Paris was broken by a brief visit to England in the early months of 1673. Leibniz had already sought the favour of Eng- lish learning by dedicating one of his publications to the Koyal Society, and he had also been greatly interested in the philosophy of Hobbes, with which to a great extent he found himself in agreement, especially as regards questions of physics, although he was strongly opposed to his political theories. In 1670 he wrote a letter to Hobbes, to which he received no answer, and after- wards he began another letter, but left it unfinished. It has recently been maintained that, up to the year 1670, Leibniz was 'more deeply affected by Hobbes than by any other of the leading spirits of the new time V When Leibniz visited London, Hobbes was still living there, but he was eighty-five years of age, and some years earlier Leibniz had heard from his countryman Olden- burg, who was secretary of the Koyal Society, that Hobbes was in his dotage. Accordingly it is not sur- prising that they did not meet. Apart from Oldenburg, the man with whom Leibniz seems to have had most intercourse during this visit to London wasKobert Boyle, the famous physicist ; but there is no reason to suppose that Leibniz gained much from his stay in England, except an additional stimulus to the study of the higher mathematics, which he carried on more systematically after his return to Paris. As a fitting conclusion of his Parisian period came the discovery of the Differential Calculus, which was practically accomplished by Leibniz 1 See Tonnies in Philos. Monatshefte, vol. xxiii. pp. 557-573. Cf. Leibniz's Letter to Holies (1670) (G. i. 85): 'I constantly maintain among my friends, and, with the help of God, I will always publicly maintain also, that I know no writer who has philosophized more accurately, more clearly, and more elegantly than you, not even excepting a man of such excellent genius as Descartes himself.' 8 INTRODUCTION in 1676. There can be no doubt that Newton was in possession of a similar method as early as 1665. He at first made known only some of the results of the method, and not the method itself. Hence an attempt has been made to show that Leibniz got hints of the method during his first visit to England, and that he was thus more or less a plagiarist of Newton. But there is nothing to confirm this, and a full consideration makes it much more likely that each discovered the method indepen- dently. Leibniz published his account of the method in 1684 : Newton's was first published in 1693. To Newton belongs the glory of priority, whatever that may be worth ; while the form which Leibniz gave to the Cal- culus, the names and the signs which he used, have come to be universally employed in preference to those of Newton l. Visit to Spinoza. Shortly before Leibniz went to London, Boineburg died ; and the visit to London was unexpectedly brought to an end in March, 1673, by the death of the Archbishop of Mainz. Leibniz was now without an official position, and during the next few years he made various unsuc- cessful attempts to obtain a diplomatic appointment. At last, in 1676, he somewhat reluctantly accepted the post of librarian to the Duke of Brunswick at Hanover, which was to be his home during the remainder of his life. During the earlier years of his residence in Paris, Leibniz had given much attention to the philosophy of Descartes and the Cartesians, with the result that he became more and more convinced of its insufficiency2. In his en- 1 See Merz, Leibniz (Blackwood's Philosophical Classics), ch. iii. and v. Cf. Guhrauer's Leibnitz, i. 170 sqq. 2 A few years after (in 1679) Leibniz writes to Philipp : 'As to the philosophy of Descartes I have no hesitation in saying abso- lutely that it leads to atheism' (G. iv. 281). And in the same year he writes to Malebranche that, while in many respects he admires Descartes, he is * convinced that his mechanics is full of LIFE AND WORKS 9 deavour after a more satisfactory metaphysic he after- wards made a considerabl_e_jjtady_ ofJPlato, and in 1676 he translated the Phaedo and the Theactetus. Towards the end of 1675 Leibniz became acquainted with the young Bohemian nobleman, Tschirnhausen, Spinoza's acute critic and correspondent, who was at that time in Paris, and who had earlier in the same year written some of the remarkable letters on account of which his name will always be associated with that of Spinoza1. Leibniz had already (in 1671) written to Spinoza from Frankfort about a question of optics ; but now Tschirn- hausen seems to have aroused in him the hope that a solution of the difficulties of Cartesianism might be found in the unpublished system of Spinoza. In November, 1675, a medical friend of Spinoza in Amster- dam (G. H. Schuller) wrote to him: * Von Tschirnhausen further mentions that he has found at Paris a man called Leibniz, remarkably learned and most skilled in various sciences, as also free from the vulgar prejudices of theology. With him he has formed an intimate acquain- tance, founded on the fact that Leibniz labours with him to pursue the perfection of the intellect, and, in fact, reckons nothing better or more useful. Von Tschirnhausen says that he is most practised in ethics, and speaks with- out any impulse derived from the passions, but by the sole dictate of reason. He adds that he is most skilled in physics, and also in metaphysical studies concerning God and the soul. Finally, he concludes that he is most worthy of having communicated to him the master's writings, if you will first give your permission, for he believes that the author will thence gain a great ad- vantage, as he promises to show at length, if the master be so pleased. But if not, do not doubt in the least that errors, his physics is too hasty, his geometry is too limited, and his metaphysics has all these faults combined' (G. i. 328). 1 Letters, 57 sqq. Van Vloten and Land, vol. ii. p. 204 ; Bruder, vol. ii. p. 321 (Letters, 61 sqq.). 10 INTKODUCTION he will honourably keep them concealed as he has promised, as in fact he has not made the slightest men- tion of them. Leibniz also highly values the Theologico- Political Treatise, on the subject of which he once wrote the master a letter, if he is not mistaken V Spinoza, in reply, recollects having some correspondence with Leibniz, but Leibniz was at that time a counsellor at Frankfort, and Spinoza would like to know, before entrusting his writings to him, what he is doing in France, and he would also like to have Tschirnhausen's opinion of Leibni/, after a longer and more intimate acquaintance. Spinoza's shyness had probably no other effect than to whet the curiosity of Leibniz, and accordingly, when he left Paris in October, 1676, he went for a week to London (where he met for the first time Newton's friend Collins) and then crossed to Amsterdam, where he stayed four weeks with Schuller, eagerly reading and criticizing every writing of Spinoza's which Schuller could give him. At last, in November, Leibniz obtained an inter- view with Spinoza at the Hague, where he seems to have spent some time. They had many conversations together regarding philosophical matters, of which Leibniz has left hardly any record except the remark that i Spinoza did not quite clearly see the defects of Descartes' laws of motion : he was surprised when I began to show him that they were inconsistent with the equality of cause and effect3.' The persistence of Leibniz ultimately induced Spinoza to show him the MS. of the Ethics (or at least a portion of it), and he seems even to have- had permission to make a copy of the leading definitions, axioms, and propositions3. What at this time most dissatisfied Leibniz was Spinoza's treatment of Final Causes. His recent study of Plato had impressed 1 Letter 70, Van Vloten and Land, vol. ii. p. 235. Foucher de Careil, Refutation inedite de Spinoza, p. Ixiv. Spinoza died in the following year, and soon afterwards the Ethics was published. LIFE AND WORKS II Leibniz with the value of teleological considerations, and he was already seeking in that direction an escape from the imperfections of the mechanical view of things. But his general hostility to Spinoza's system did not show itself until ten years later, when he had settled the essential points of his own doctrine of substance. At this time Leibniz was still seeking light in every quarter. Residence in Hanover. Correspondence and Growth of his System. Leibniz arrived at Hanover in the last days of 1676. Efforts had already been made to convert him to the Roman Catholic faith, and he had begun a correspondence with Pellisson (a distinguished convert from Protes- tantism) in the hope of finding some means of Church reunion. This correspondence led to others, of which the most important was one with Bossuet. But, though Leibniz was more or less occupied with these discussions throughout the rest of his life, nothing practical came of them. Bossuet's attitude in the discussion was only too well expressed in his exclamation regarding Leibniz : Utinam ex nostris esset ! ; Would that he were one of us ! ' And Leibniz was too much of a scientific inquirer to unite two opposed religious communions. He might draw up a statement of dogma to which both sides could assent *, but inevitably it would express the real belief of neither. The endeavour to convert Leibniz was not given up for a very long time, and a brief visit of his to Rome in 1689 seems to have caused a flutter of excitement. He was offered the librarianship of the Vatican and other posts with a vista of preferment ; but conversion was so far from his mind that we hear of him bringing from the Catacombs a piece of glass, reddened with the blood of martyrs, in order to submit it to chemical analysis ! 1 He actually attempted this, in what has been grandiloquently called the Systema Theologicum, written in 1686. 12 INTRODUCTION It was during the early years of his residence in Hanover that Leibniz worked out the leading ideas of his system. Disappointed in his hope of finding in Spinoza a saviour from the errors of Descartes, and being the rather confirmed, by Spinoza's conclusions, in his conviction of the insufficiency of any merely mechanical interpretation of things, he turned with renewed interest to Plato1, with the result that towards 1680 he had reached the conception of substance as essentially active force. It is possible also that, in spite of his general dissatisfaction with Spinoza's position, some of Spinoza's ideas (such as that of the conatus or self-preserving tendency of things) may have contributed to the develop- ment of his new view of substance. One further step was needed to complete the theory, namely, the recogni- tion that the force constituting a substance is not a universal world-principle, but something individual— that there are substances which are forces. To this position he seems to have attained about 1684 or a little later, through a return to the consideration of Aristotle and the Peripatetic Schools, whose views he had set aside in his boyhood, nearly twenty-five years before. The main ideas of his philosophy (such as his conception of ' simple substance' and his pre-established harmony) . were first stated in the correspondence with Arnauld, which took place between 1686 and 1690. This correspondence, however, was not published as a whole until 1846 ; and the learned world was first made aware that Leibniz had worked out a philosophical system of his own by two papers which he published in 1695— one (the Specimen Dynamicum) in the Leipzig Acta Eruditontm, and the other (the Systeme Nouveau) in the French Journal des Savants. Leibniz uses the term 'monad' for the first time in 1697. 1 ' Of all the ancient philosophers I find Plato the most satis- factory in regard to metaphysics.' Letlre a M. Bourguet (1714) (E. 723 a ; G. iii. 568). LIFE AND WOKKS 13 The 'Nouveaux JEssais' and the l Tfieodicee.' Having thus definitely fixed his philosophical system-1, and having published its leading principles, Leibniz gradually expounded it in detail, for the most part by means of correspondence and criticism. Hitherto he had given most attention to ontological or purely meta- physical problems. But now he began to consider more carefully the theory of knowledge and the psychological questions that are connected with it. Locke's Essay was published in 1690, and a few years afterwards Leibniz read it, writing (as was his custom) notes and comments as he read. Some of these criticisms were in 1697 sen^ to Locke, who treated them with contempt, and made no reply2. In 1703 Leibniz wrote the Nouveaux Essais sur I'Entendement humain, a long dialogue, in which the views of Locke and of himself are set in contrast throughout a discussion dealing with the subjects of Locke's Essay chapter by chapter. This book was evidently intended to call forth a rejoinder from Locke. But before it was ready for publication Locke died (in 1704) ; and Leibniz, saying that he ' greatly disliked publishing refutations of dead authors,' and that he now 'preferred to publish his thoughts independently of another person's,' allowed the Nouveaux Essais to remain in manuscript, so that the book was first published by Kaspe in 1765, nearly fifty years after Leibniz's death. After writing some other papers on psychological and 1 In 1697 he writes to Thomas Burnet of Kemnay : ' I have changed and changed again, according as new light came to me ; and it is only about twelve years since I found what satisfies me, and arrived at demonstrations regarding matters which did not seem capable of demonstration/ (G-. iii. 205.) * Leibniz (in 1714) says that he was not surprised at Locke's disdain. 'The difference between our principles was somewhat too great, and what I maintained seemed to him to be paradox.' He adds that Locke ' had subtlety and dexterity, and he had a kind of superficial metaphysics which he knew how to make the most of; but he did not know the method of mathematicians.' Ltttre a Eemond (E. 703 b ; G. iii. 612). 14 INTRODUCTION epistemological subjects, Leibniz, in 1710, published his Tfieodicee, the one great work of his which was printed in his lifetime. It was written, not continuously, but at intervals, in a very diffuse and discursive style, and its purpose was to develop the principles of its author's philosophy in maintaining, against the 'arguments of Pierre Bayle, the harmony of faith and reason, and to 'vindicate the ways of God to man/ The writing of the Theodicee was suggested to Leibniz as the result of conversations with Queen Sophia Charlotte of Prussia, who also induced him to write various other philo- sophical papers, and who encouraged him in his plans for the founding of an Academy at Berlin. Besides the exposition of his system which he gives in such elaborate works as the Nouveaux Essais and the Theodicee, Leibniz met the objections of critics and suggested new applications of his principles in the course of a varied correspondence. On questions of mathematics and physics in their con- nexion with metaphysics, he corresponded with John Bernouilli for more than twenty years (from 1694 to 1716), and for ten years (1706-1716) he discussed with Des Bosses the possibility of combining his philosophy of substance with the presuppositions of the doctrine of transubstantiation. Further, among many other epi- stolary discussions, mention may be made of Leibniz's correspondence, during the last two years of his life, with Bourguet on the chief doctrines of his philosophy, with special reference to biological questions, and with Clarke on space and time and the Divine attributes. Founding of Academies. Closing Tears. The amazing intellectual activity of Leibniz found expression in many other writings. During the greater part of his residence at Hanover he worked at a history of the house of Brunswick, in connexion with which he travelled much and ransacked the libraries of Germany and Italy. He suggested the development of mining in LIFE AND WORKS 15 the Harz Mountains, and in connexion with this he studied and wrote on geological subjects and on the currency. But, above all, the interest of Leibniz in these later years lay in the endeavour to extend science and civilization throughout Europe. With this end in view, he, who (according to Frederick the Great) was an Academy in himself, succeeded after much effort in obtaining the foundation of an Academy at Berlin, of which he himself was appointed the first president (1700). Afterwards he made long-continued but un- successful attempts to induce the King of Poland, the Czar, and the Emperor to found similar Academies at Dresden, St. Petersburg, and Vienna. He had Inter- views with Peter the Great, whom he expected to become 'the Solon of Russia,' and he lived for some time in Vienna, where he tried to bring about an alliance between the Czar and the Emperor. Charles VI favoured his projects for the founding of learned societies, and he was also strongly supported by Prince Eugene of Savoy, for whom in 1714 he wrote the Monadologie (or, as Gerhardt maintains, the Principes de la Nature et de la Grace). But Europe was full of wars and rumours of wars, and the peaceful plans of Leibniz were set aside. The Berlin Academy had a struggling existence, and no other was founded until long after Leibniz's death. The happiest years of the life of Leibniz were now over. The Duke of Brunswick1 died in 1698, and Leibniz seems gradually to have lost favour with his son and successor, our George I. After the death of his friends, 'the two Electresses,' Sophia and Sophia Charlotte (the mother and the sister of George I), Leibniz's position became intolerable. George I succeeded to the English crown in 1714, and his prejudices against Leibniz, shown in his displeasure on account of the latter 's residence in Vienna, were encouraged by some of Newton's friends, 1 Successor of the duke who had originally appointed Leibniz to the librarianship at Hanover. l6 INTRODUCTION whom he met in England. Leibniz thought of leaving Hanover ; but in later years his health had been some- what broken, and on November 14, 1716, he died during an attack of gout. His secretary, Eckhart, invited all the people of the Court to his funeral, but not one of them came, and Eckhart alone followed his master's body to the grave. An acquaintance of Leibniz, John Ker of Kersland1, who had come to Hanover on the very day of Leibniz's death, says that he was buried ' more like a robber than, what he really was, the ornament of his country.' No minister of religion was present ; for Leibniz was parcus deorum cultor et infrequens, and his absence from church was counted to him for irreligion, so that from priests and people he got the nickname Ajjdvenix (the Low German for Glaubet nichts, believer in nothing). The Berlin Academy and the Koyal Society of London took no notice of his death ; but a year afterwards Fontenelle commemorated it in a fine oration, delivered before the Parisian Academy. Personal Characteristics. , As to the personal characteristics of Leibniz, Eckhart tells us that he was of middle height, with a somewhat large head, dark-brown hair, and small but very sharp eyes. He was near-sighted, but had no difficulty in reading, and himself wrote a very small hand. His lungs were not strong, and he had a thin but clear voice, with a difficulty in pronouncing gutturals. He was broad- shouldered and always walked with his head bent for- ward, so that he looked like a man with a humped back. In figure he was slim rather than stout, and his legs 1 A leader of the Scottish Cameronians. He lived on political intrigue, and when his resources in England were failing him he presented to the Emperor, through Leibniz, a project for privateer- ing and buccaneering against the Spaniards in the Pacific. In the Political Memoir containing Ker's proposals there is a curious medley of religious considerations and the hope of gain. Cf. Foucher de Careil, iv. 272 sqq. LIFE AND WORKS 17 were crooked. His household arrangements (if they can be called * arrangements ') were very irregular. He had no fixed hours for meals, but, when a convenient oppor- tunity came in the course of his studies, he sent out for something to eat. He once made a proposal of marriage (when he was fifty years of age), but the lady took time to consider, and (Fontenelle says) i this gave Leibniz also time to consider, and he never married.' He slept little, but well : he often spent the night in his chair, and sometimes he would remain in it for several days at a time. This enabled him to do a great deal of work ; but it led to illness, for which, disliking physicians, he em- ployed remedies more ' heroic ' than wise. He enjoyed intercourse with all sorts and conditions of men, believing that he could always learn something even from the most ignorant. ' Cum Socrate semper ad disc endum par atus sum.9 l He spoke well of everybody,' says Eckhart, 'and made the best of everything ' (er kelwte alles zum Besten). He often congratulates himself on being self-taught (avroSt'SaKTos), and thus able to avoid acquiescence in super- ficial, ready-made knowledge and to strike out paths of his own. For he is ever (he teljs us) ' eager to penetrate into all things more deeply than is usually done and to find something new.' 'When,' says Diderot, 'one considers oneself and compares one's talents with those of a Leibniz, one is tempted to throw books away and seek some hidden corner of the world where one may die in peace. < This man's mind was a foe of disorder : the most entangled things fell into order when they entered it. He com-' bined two great qualities which are almost incompatible with one another — the spirit of discovery and that of method ; and the most determined .and varied study, through which he accumulated knowledge of the most widely differing kinds, weakened neither the one quality nor the other. In the fullest meaning these words can bear, he was a philosopher and a mathematician V 1 Encyclopedic, (Euvres (Assezat's ed.), vol. xv. p. 440. C 1 8 INTRODUCTION The Works of Leibniz. Many of the most important philosophical works of Leibniz were not published till after his death. Large quantities of manuscript were preserved in the Royal Library at Hanover, and successive editors have con- tinually drawn upon it for publication. The chief editions of the philosophical works are that of Erdmann (1840) and that of Gerhardt (1875-90), the latter being the most complete. In 1866 Janet published an edition in French, containing the principal works as they are given in Erdmann, with the addition of the correspondence between Leibniz and Arnauld, which had not been pub- lished when Erdmann's edition appeared. The mathe- matical works were published by Gerhardt in seven volumes (1850-63). Of the historical and political works Onno Klopp published ten volumes (1864-77). Toucher de Careil also published in seven volumes (1859-75) some of Leibniz's political works, along with his corre- spondence on the reunion of Christendom and his writings in connexion with the founding of academies. In addition to these may be mentioned the old edition of Dutens in six volumes (1768), which contains some things not in- cluded in any of the others, and the booklet of Mollat (1885), containing some papers of Leibniz on ethics and jurisprudence. The following are the principal philosophical works of Leibniz, with the dates at which they were written or published. The letters J. S. indicate those which appeared in the Journal des Savants, and the letters A. E. those which appeared in the Acta Eruditorum. Those marked with an asterisk were published in Leibniz's lifetime. Correspondence with Philipp and others regarding the Philosophy of Descartes, 1679-80. (In French.) G. iv. 281 sqq. *Medifationes de Cognitione, Vcritate et Ideis, A. E. 1684. G. iv. 422 ; E. 79. Correspondence icith Arnauld, 1686-90. (In French.) G. ii. i. Pub- lished by Grotefend, 1846. LIFE AND WORKS 19 *Extrait d'une Lettre a M. Bayle. Published in the Nouvelks de la Republique des Lettres, 1687. G. iii. 51 ; E. 104. De Vera Methodo Philosophiae et Theologiae, 1690. G. vii. 323 ; E. 109. *Si I'Essence du Corps consiste dans I'Etendue, J. S. 1691 and 1693. G. iv. 464; E. 112. Animadversiones in partem generalem Principiorum Cartesianorum, 1692. Published by Guhrauer, 1844. G. iv. 350. Mentioned by Leibniz in a letter to Bernouilli, 1697. *De Notionibus Juris et Justitiae, preface to Codex Juris Gentium Diplo- maticus, published in 1693. E. 118. *De Primae Philosophiae Emendatione et de Notione Substantiae, A. E. 1694. G. iv. 468 ; E. 121. *Systeme Nouveau de la Nature et de la Communication des Substances, J. S; 1695. G. iv. 471 ; E. 124. Also three Eclaircissements du Nouveau Systeme, J. S. 1696. Schreiben an Gabriel Wagner vom Nutzen der Vernunftkunst oder Logik, 1696. Published by Guhrauer, 1838. G. vii. 514 ; E. 418. De Eerum Originatione radicali, 1697. G. vii. 302; E. 147. Published by Erdmann, 1840. *De ipsa Natura, sive de Vi insita Actionibusque Creaturarum, A. E. 1698. G. iv. 504 ; E. 154. Various papers (without titles) on Cartesianism, written between 1700 and 1702. G. iv. 393 sqq. ; E. 177. Considerations sur la Doctrine d'un Esprit Universel unique, 1702. G. vi. 529 ; E. 178. Published by Erdmann, 1840. Sur ce qui passe les Sens et Id Matiere (Letter to Queen Sophia Charlotte of Prussia), 1702. G. vi. 488. Nouveaux Essais sur VEntendement humain, 1704. G. v. 41 ; E. 194. Published by Raspe, 1765. * Considerations sur les Principesde Vie et sur les Natures plastiques (Histoire des Ouvrages des Savants, 1705). G. vi. 539 ; E. 429. Ad rev. Patrem des Bosses Epistolae 71, 1706-16. G. ii. 291 ; E. 434, &c. E. gives 29 only. Dutens gives 70. De Modo distinguendi Phaenomena realia ab imaginariis. G. vii. 319 ; E. 443- Animadversiones ad Joh. G. Wachteri Librum de recondita Hebraeorum philo- sophia, c. 1708 (including the 'Refutation of Spinoza'). Pub- lished by Foucher de Careil, 1854. Commentatio de Anima Brutorum, 1710. G. vii. 328 ; E. 463. Published by Kortholt, 1735. * Essais de Theodicee sur la Bonte de Dieu, la Liberte de I'Homme et I'Origine du Mai, 1710. G. vi. i ; E. 468. Von der Gluckseligkeit, 1710 (?). G. vii. 86 ; E. 671. Published by Guhrauer, 1838. C 2 20 INTRODUCTION Principes de la Nature et de la Grace, fondes en Raison, 1714. G. vi. 598 ; E. 714. First published in L'Europe Savante, Nov. 1718. La Monadologie, 1714. G. vi. 607 ; E. 705. Germ, trans. Kohler (Jena), 1726. Lat. trans. A. E. 1721. Original French in E. 1840. Correspondence with Nicholas Remond, 1713-16. (In French.) G. iii. 599 ; E. 701, &c. Correspondence with Bourgiiet, 1709-16. (In French.) G. iii. 539; E. 718, &c. Correspondence with Clarke, 1715-16. (In French.) G. vii. 347 ; E. 746. PART II. GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF LEIBNIZ. Statement of Leibniz's Problem : How can that which is continuous consist of indivisible Elements ? IN the preface to his The'odice'e1 Leibniz declares that * there are two famous labyrinths, in which our reason often goes astray : the one relates to the great question of liberty and necessity, especially in regard to the production and origin of evil ; the other consists in the discussion of continuity and of the indivisible points which appear to be its elements, and this question involves the consideration of the infinite. The former of these perplexes almost all the human race, the latter claims the attention of philosophers alone/ Accordingly, while a right under- standing of the principle of continuity is of the utmost speculative importance, the practical value of a true knowledge of necessity is equally great. Thus, Leibniz makes his Theodicee an investigation of the meaning of liberty and necessity, while in others of his writings he oifers a solution of the problem which he describes as the special perplexity of philosophers. It is this latter problem with which we are here mainly concerned. The philosophical work of Leibniz was an endeavour to reconcile the notion of substance as con- tinuous with the contrary notion of substance as consisting of indivisible elements. The opposition of these two notions 1 E. 470 a ; G. vi. 29. 22 INTRODUCTION seemed to him to arise from an inadequate conception of substance, and the task he set himself was that of deepening the current notion of substance, or, as he him- self would have put it, finding a better hypothesis than that which had satisfied his Cartesian predecessors. Stated in another way the problem is : How are we to interpret the relation of whole and parts so that the continuity or complete unity of the whole shall not be in conflict with the definiteness or real diversity of the parts ? To say that the whole is continuous or really one seems to mean that, if it is divisible at all, it is infinitely divisible. If it were not infinitely divisible, it would consist of insoluble ultimate elements, and would thus be discontinuous. Accordingly, if the whole be really con- tinuous there seem to be no fixed boundaries or lines of division within it, that is to say, no real, but only arbitrary parts \ On the other hand, if the whole consists of real parts and not merely possible subdivisions, these parts must be definite, bounded, separate from one another, and consequently the whole which they constitute must be, not a real continuous unity, but a mere collection or arbitrary unity. Nevertheless, we cannot hold either that the whole is real and the parts unreal, or that the parts are real and the whole unreal. Quantitative or extensive Notion of Substance held ly Des- cartes and Spinoza, on the one hand, and ly the Atomists on the other. The philosophy of Spinoza, with its cardinal principle that * Determination is negation,' practically amounted to an assertion of the unity and continuity of the whole at the expense of the reality of the parts. According to 1 For instance, the spectrum is continuous. There is no limit to the number of varieties of colour that may be discriminated in the rainbow : the usual division into seven colours is an arbitrary arrangement made by observers. It probably originated in a sug- gested analogy with the musical scale. GENERAL PRINCIPLES 23 Spinoza, 'substance ' is ' that which is in itself and is conceived through itself; in other words, that, the conception of which does not need the conception of another thing from, which it must be formed V That is to say, substance is the unconditioned, or that which is not conditioned or determined by anything other than itself. There is ambiguity in the statement. It may mean e'ither that substance is sel£conditioned or that it is absolutely unconditioned, to the exclusion of all determination. In the one case substance would be a real system of reciprocal determinations ; in the other, it would be unbroken being, to which every determination is foreign. The latter is the dominant aspect of substance in the philosophy of Spinoza. That aspect alone is con- sistent with the principle that i Determination is negation.' Consequently his position amounts to saying that sub- stance can have no real parts. For the very meaning of a part implies that it must be determined or conditioned by other parts 2. In contrary opposition to this, there is the theory of atoms and the void, which Leibniz tells us at one time charmed his imagination 3. To affirm the real existence of indivisible material atoms is to deny the infinite divisibility of matter. Accordingly, if the atoms con- stitute the ultimate reality of the world, its unity is destroyed, its continuity becomes an illusion. However numerous the atoms may be, they can together constitute no true unity, i but only a collection or heaping up of parts ad infinitum4.' Atomism thus endeavours to establish the reality of the parts at the expense of the whole. It is necessary, then, to lay bare the presuppositions of these contrary theories in order to find the elements of truth in each and to reconcile them in a more compre- hensive view. The doctrine of Spinoza is the consistent 1 Ethics, Part i. def. 3, Hale White's Tr. 2 Ibid. Part i. prop. 12 and 13. 3 New System, § 3. * Loc. cit. 24 INTRODUCTION logical development of the principles involved in the position of Descartes1. In this connexion it is Descartes's special theories that Leibniz has mostly in view, although his arguments are equally applicable to the more thorough metaphysic of Spinoza. ' Spinoza,' he tells us, 'has done nothing but cultivate certain seeds of the philosophy of M. Descartes2.' Descartes endeavoured to reach absolute metaphysical certainty by a method which was after- wards more clearly and fully applied by Spinoza, who denned it in his great principle that l Determination is negation/ The essence of Descartes's method of doubt is the endeavour to attain certainty by stripping from experience (as it is given in common consciousness) all specific qualities or determinations, on the ground that no contradiction in terms is involved in regarding each of these qualities by itself as non-existent or other than it is. The result of the method is to give, as the residual ultimate certainty, nothing but the instrument by which the process of stripping has been carried out, viz. the 1 ' Cartesianae disciplinae intemperantia Spinozae doctrinam par it ; in hoc sententia totum reperire est Leibnitium ' (Lemoine, Quid sit materia apud Leibnitium, p. 52). ; The philosophy of Descartes . . . seems to lead straight to the opinions of Spinoza, who dared to say what Descartes carefully avoided.' (G. iv. 3464) a Lettre a I' Abbe Nicaise (1697) (E. 139 h; G. ii. 563). Leibniz, especially in his earlier days, recognized that his philosophy had much in common with that of Spinoza., although, as time went on, it became more and more evident to him that they were funda- mentally at variance. Thus, in an early letter (February, 1678), we find Leibniz writing: 'I find in it' [the Ethics] 'plenty of fine thoughts agreeing with mine, as is known to some of my friends who are also friends of Spinoza. But there are also paradoxes which seem to me unreal and not even plausible. As, for example, that there is only one substance, namely God ; that created things are modes or accidents of God ; that our mind has no wider outlook [nihil amplius percipere~\ after this life ; that God Himself thinks indeed, but nevertheless neither understands nor wills , that all things happen by a certain necessity of fate ; that God acts not for an end but by a certain necessity of nature, which is verbally to retain, but really to give up, providence and immortality^; I regard this book as a dangerous one for people -yrho will give themselves the trouble to go deeply into it, for others do not care to under- stand it.' Archivfur Geschichte d. Philosophic, vol. iii. p. 75. GENERAL PRINCIPLES 25 thinking Ego, without any specific thought. If we challenge the reality of this instrument, we do so by means of the instrument itself, and so involve ourselves in self-contradiction. The thinking Ego cannot be thought non-existent : to think its non-existence would be a con- tradiction in terms-. Spinoza's advance upon1 this was merely to pass from Descartes's practical method of attaining truth (namely, the discarding: of specific deter- minations) to the general metaphysical principle which the method implied, the principle, namely, that the essence or reality of a thing is that which remains after the differences in its states and qualities have been thought away, or that which is common to all its forms and manifestations, and consequently that the ultimate reality or substance is that which is free from all specific determinations, that which includes or is common to everything because it is not (specially) anything. Now when we rigorously apply this principle,, that the reality of substance is that which remains after all specific or differential qualities have been removed, we are left with nothing but quantity — either, as in. the case of Spinoza, quantity of substance in general l ; or, as in the case of Descartes, quantity of a specific substance, that is to say quantity of one quality. Thus Descartes's position is that in addition to the one true and perfect substance, God, whose existence is externally uncon- ditioned, there are two created substances, whose exis- tence is not conditioned by anything finite, but by infinite 1 It is true that Spinoza regards substance as indivisible, in the sense that it has no real parts ; and this may seem inconsistent with the contention that Spinoza's substance is merely quantita- tive. But the contradiction is Spinoza's : it is a fragment of the great fissure of inconsistency that traverses his whole system, namely, the confounding of a substance possessing infinite attri-|| butes with a substance whose reality is reached by the exclusion |1 of all specific determinations. If we hold strictly to the second of these views of substance, then substance can be said to be in- divisible only on the ground that there is nothing to divide. Cf. Spinoza, Ethics, Part i. prop. 12 and 13, with Tractatus de Intettectus Emendations, 108, ii. iii. 26 INTRODUCTION substance alone. These are bodily substance and think- ing substance. They are mutually opposite : the one is what the other is not. Neither is conditioned by the other nor dependent upon it. The essential attribute of bodily substance is extension, that of thinking sub. stance is thought. All the specific qualities of created things are reducible to one or other of these as a common quality ; and consequently the essence or reality of created substance comes to be either extension without specific contents or thought without a specific object. In other words, bodily substance is quantity of one determination, namely extension ; while thinking sub- stance is quantity of one other determination, namely thought. Thus the presupposition of the Cartesian systems is a purely quantitative relation of whole and parts \ The same presupposition in another form underlies the Atomist philosophy. The atoms are material par- ticles, and the whole consists of their aggregation. If the theory is self-consistent they must be regarded as 1 Cf. Descartes, Principia, Part ii. § 8 : ' Quantity and number differ only in thought [ratione] from that which has quantity and is numbered.' § 1 1 : 'It will be easy to discern that it is the same extension which constitutes the nature of body as of space, and that these two things are mutually diverse only as the nature of the genus and species differs from that of the individual, provided we reflect on the idea we have of any body, taking a stone for example, and reject all that is not essential to the nature of body. In the first place, then, hardness may be rejected, because if the stone were liquefied or reduced to powder it would no longer possess hardness, and yet would not cease to be a body ; colour also may be thrown out of account, because we have frequently seen stones so transparent as to have no colour ; again, we may reject weight, because we have the case of fire, which, though very light. is still a body ; and finally, we may reject cold, heat, and all the other qualities of this sort, either because they are not considered as in the stone, or because, with the change of these qualities, the stone is not supposed to have lost the nature of body. After this examination we shall find that nothing remains in the idea of body, except that it is something extended in length, breadth, and depth ; and this something is comprised in our idea of space, not only of that which is full of body, but even of what is called void space' (Veitch's Tr.). Cf. Principia, Part i. §§ 51-53, 63-65. GENERAL PRINCIPLES 27 homogeneous, and the specific qualities of things must arise from the variety of their combinations. They could not all really exist and be different from one another without some of them being complex. And in any case the very essence of the theory is that the whole should be taken as a sum or totality, a quantity of parts. Leibniz's non-quantitative or intensive Notion of Substance, developed through criticism of Cartesian andAtomist views regarding material Substance. Accordingly, the essence of Leibniz's argument is that a quantitative conception of the relation of whole and parts aifords an inadequate theory of substance. The common element in the contrary positions of the Cartesians and the Atomists is the explicit or implicit reduction of qualitative to quantitative differences \ And it appears to Leibniz that the solution of the dilemma , / is to be found in the opposite hypothesis, namely, that the essence of substance is non-quantitative, and that the relation of whole and parts must be conceived as L The Identity of Indiscernibles and the Law of Continuity. The indivisible having thus been established, there remains the question of continuity and the infinite. As we have seen, a quantitative continuum cannot have indivisible parts. But, as the actual indivisible elements of reality are essentially perceptive, real continuity must also be a continuity of perception. As each Monad is a part or element of the universe, in the sense that each represents it or reflects it as in a mirror from some particular angle, in some special aspect, the whole must perception and appetition, although we do not distinctly know the imperceptible elements of the confused perceptions, by which the imperceptible elements of bodies are expressed.' Epistola ad Bierlingntm (1711) (E. 678 a ; G. vii. 501). 1 Monadology, § i. 2 Ibid. § 7. 3 Ibid. §§ 3-6. * As to the contrast between Leibniz's view of substance and that of Locke, see Locke's Essay, Fraser's ed, . vol. i. pp. 399 sqq. ty GENERAL PRINCIPLES 37 be the infinite totality of Monads, representing the universe from every possible point of view. And thus, while the Monads are entirely separate from one another, each must represent the universe in a way which differs to the least possible extent from the representation given by some other. No two Monads (and a fortiori no two Y things, which are all aggregates of Monads; can be exactly y the same : no thing can have a merely numerical differ- *""" ence from another. The Monads are essentially non- quantitative, and number by itself is merely a measure of quantity. The Monads differ from one another in quality or intension alone, so that two Monads not differing in quality are impossible. This is the doctrine of Leibniz which is usually called the cerniblesV It is simply his law of continuity in a ^ negative form. The number of Monads must be in- finite 2 : otherwise the universe would not be represented from every possible point of view, and would thus be imperfect. But if the number of Monads is infinite, and if every Monad differs in quality from every other, then the Monads must be such that they might be considered as a series, each term or member of which differs from the next by an infinitely small degree of quality, i. e. by a degree of quality less than any which can be assigned. •1>- Leibniz explains his principle of continuity in a letter y quoted by his biographer, Guhrauer3. *I think, then,' 1 < There are no two indiscernible individuals. A clever gentle- man of my acquaintance, talking with me in presence of Mme. the Electress, in the garden of Herrenhausen, was of opinion that he could quite well find two leaves entirely alike. Mnie. the Electress would not believe it, and he spent a long time vainly seeking them. Two drops of water or of milk, looked at through a microscope, will be found discernible. This is an argument against atoms, to which, no less than to the void, the principles of true metaphysic are opposed ... To suppose two indiscernible things is to suppose the — • same thing under two names.' IF"*5 Lettre a Clarke, §§4 and 6 (E. 755 b, 756 a ; G. vii. 372). Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. ii. ch. 27, § 3 (E. 277 b ; G. v. 214). 2 Du Bois-Reymond compares the infinite series of Monads to the ordinates of a curve, which grow from nothing to infinity. 3 G. W. F. von Leibnitz, eine Biographic, vol. i., Anmerkungen, p. 32. 38 INTRODUCTION he says, ' that I have good reasons for believing that all the different classes of beings, the totality of which forms the universe, are, in the ideas of God, who knows distinctly their essential gradations, merely like so many ordinates of one and the same curve, the relations of which do not allow of others being put between any two of them, because that would indicate disorder and imper- fection. Accordingly men are linked with animals, these with plants, and these again with fossils, which in their turn are connected with those bodies which sense and imagination represent to us as completely dead and inor- ganic [informes]. But the law of continuity requires that, when the essential determinations of any being approximate to those of another, all the properties of the former must gradually approximate to those of the latter. Therefore all the orders of natural beings must necessarily form only one chain, in which the different classes, like so many links, are so closely connected with one -another that it is impossible for sense or imagination to determine exactly the point where any one of -them begins or ends ; all the species which border upon or which occupy, so to speak, dis- putable territory [regions d" inflexion et de rebroussement '] being necessarily ambiguous and endowed with charac- teristics which may equally be ascribed to neighbouring species. Thus, for instance, the existence of zoophytes, or, as Buddeus2 calls them, Plant- animals, does not imply monstrosity, but it is indeed agreeable to the order of nature that they should exist. And so strongly do I hold The Academy of Berlin declared this letter to be spurious ; but there seems no good reason to doubt its genuineness. All they proved was that the letter had not been addressed to the person to whom it was said to have been addressed. See also Introduction, Part iii, p. 83 note, and New Essays, Introduction, p. 376. Cf. Locke, Essay, bk. iiL ch. 6, § 12, Eraser's ed., vol. i. p. 67 ; cf. note on p. 380. 1 Literally, places where the curve or chain turns back upon itself. 2 Probably Johannes Franciscus Buddaeus (1667-1729), Professor of Philosophy at Halle, and afterwards of Theology at Jena. Ho published many books, mostly on moral philosophy. GENERAL PRINCIPLES 39 to the principle of continuity that not only should I not be astonished to learn that there had been found beings which, as regards several properties — for instance, those of feeding or multiplying themselves — might pass for vegetables as well as for animals, and which upset the common rules, founded upon the supposition of a complete \ and absolute separation of the different orders of beings which together fill the universe : I say, I should be so little astonished at it that I am even convinced that there must be such beings, and that natural history will perhaps some day come to know them, when it has further studied that infinity of living beings whose smallness conceals them from ordinary observation, and which lie hid in the bowels of the earth and in the depths of the waters * . . . ' T}ie pre-established Harmony between Substances. There is, then, in the system of the Monads a perfectly continuous and infinite gradation of intension, that is to say, of perception or representation, combined with appe- tition or spontaneous change. And thus the universe is at once continuous and not only infinitely divisible, but infinitely divided, consisting of an infinity of real ele- ments 2. But we still have to consider how the principle I of continuity, as thus interpreted, is consistent with the B changes which take place in real things. In the system of Monads the principle of continuity corresponds to the 1 that is to say, by an addition not conditioned by any special law. But there are certain numerical series in which the terms are not mutually indifferent (nor immediately reducible to a set of mutually indifferent terms), but are arranged, or rather proceed from one another, according to. a definite law, which law is of such a kind that, although it never brings the series actually to an end, it results in the sum of the series approaching more and more nearly to some finite quantity. Accordingly it is held that, if the series be regarded as consisting of an infinite number of terms, the difference between the sum of its terms and the finite quantity will be infinitely little, and therefore practically negligible. This ' practically negligible ' is the keystone of the bridge between algebraic quantity and geometrical, physical, or any other kind of relation. Strictly speaking, if the series be regarded as a pure sum, and therefore ultimately analyzable into an addition of homogeneous units (i + i + i, &c., or n + n + n, &c.), the finitude of its sum is incompatible with its having an infinite number of terms. It is only inasmuch as the series is regarded, not as a merely quantitative unity, but as a unity deter- mined by a characteristic law or principle, that we are entitled to disregard the ' infinitely little ' difference between the sum of its terms and the finite quantity. There can be no absolute * infinitely little ' in mere quantity. The ' infinitely little' here considered is * infinitely little ' as determined by the law or character of the particular series. That is to say, we are certain that the law of the series holds unchangeably, however far the process of analysis may be carried ; and we have thus inferential certainty regarding the result of the analysis (the equation of the sum of the terms to the whole finite quantity), even although we may be unable actually to count each one of the terms. It is the law 8o INTRODUCTION or principle of the series which enables us to say that the ' infinitely little ' difference may be neglected because the character of the series is not affected by it. But in neglecting this * infinitely little ' difference, because of the special character or law of the series, we have virtually passed from the unity of mere quantity to a unity of character, a unity in which the parts are not entirely indifferent to the whole and to one another, but are connected in accordance with some special principle. We have thus given an indefinite increase of elasticity to the formulae of Algebra and have prepared the way for an algebraic representation and calculus not merely of the elementary space-unities (figures) of the Greek Geometry, but also of more comprehensive geometrical unities of which these are elements, and further of physical unities and indeed of any unity the elements of which are in themselves capable of a sufficiently accurate quantitative expression. For instance, the phenomena with which Physics deals are differences of a unity, elements in a whole. But the unity, the whole, is not one of quantity merely. And yet its elements are capable of quantitative expression with a degree of accuracy such that its dif- ference from absolute accuracy may be neglected so far as physical science is concerned. Consequently it becomes possible to state and to work out nggfelems of physical science in terms of Algebra. The Infinitesimal Calculus and the Principle of Becoming or System. The practical development of this possibility is the function of the Infinitesimal Calculus of Leibniz and Newton3. As we have already seen, the Analytical 1 A succinct account of the famous controversy regarding the discovery of this method, and of the different forms in which Leibniz and Newton expressed it/will be found in Dr. William- son's article * Infinitesimal Calculus ' in the pth ed. of the Encyclo- paedia Britannica. Cf. Merz, History of European Thmight in the Nineteenth Century, i. 100-103. STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 8 1 Geometry reduces the discontinuity of Synthetic Geo- metry to the relative continuity of number, or quantity of homogeneous units. But number as a sum of finite units (even though it may take the form of an infinite series) is still to some extent discontinuous. It may, however, be made continuous by regarding its elements not as finite units, but as t infinitesimals ' or infinitely little quantities. In other words, any numerical unit we may choose to employ may be subdivided infinitely, and thus every finite number may be regarded as the sum of an infinite series of infinitely small terms. This is the basis of the Infinitesimal Calculus as originally conceived by Leibniz. It may be otherwise expressed by saying that the series of finite numbers or quantities is ulti- mately to be expressed, not as a series of terms which grow by finite increments (like i-f-(i + i) + (i + i+i) &c.), but as a series whose terms flow into one another, their differences being infinitely small. That is to say, any variable magnitude must be regarded as increasing or diminishing by infinitely small increments or decrements. The work of the Calculus is to determine the relations between unknown quantities or magnitudes, not by considering them merely as fixed wholes and directly finding equations between them, but indirectly, by treat- ing the quantities as variables or as growing, and in the first place finding equations between their elements or differences *. 1 From one point of view it may be regarded as the solving of the problem of Achilles and the tortoise. Cf. Lettre a M. Foucher (1693) (E. 118 a; G. i. 416) : 'As to indivisibles, in the sense of the mere extremities of a time or of a line, we cannot conceive new extremi- ties, nor actual nor potential parts in them. Thus points are neither large nor small, and no leap is needed to pass them. Yet the continuous, although it everywhere has such indivisibles, is not composed of them, as the objections of sceptics seem to suppose. There is, in my opinion, nothing insurmountable in these objections, as will be found if they are put into strict form. Father Gregory of St. Vincent has excellently shown, by the Calculus of infinite divisibility, the place where Achilles should overtake the tortoise which starts before him, according to the proportion of their velocities. Thus Geometry dissipates these apparent difficulties.' 0 82 INTRODUCTION Accordingly, for instance, Newton regarded all geo- metrical magnitudes as capable of generation by con- tinuous motion. Lines may be regarded as generated by the motion of points, surfaces by that of lines, and solids by that of surfaces. That is to say, these figures are dis- tinct from one another, not absolutely, but merely in the degree in which they possess certain characteristics. The difference between the point and the line is an infinitely small degree of length, the difference between the line and the surface is an infinitely small degree of breadth, the difference between the surface and the solid is an in- finitely small degree of depth. * Motion, ' in Newton's way of putting it, is in this connexion merely a metaphor for continuity. Again, in physical science we have to deal with phenomena which not merely are variable but are continually varying, and the Infinitesimal Calculus is of the utmost value in enabling us to state the laws of these variations, that is to say, to establish proportions between different sets of constantly changing phenomena. The value of the Infinitesimal Calculus in the interpre- tation of nature rests ultimately on this, that the con- ception of ' infinitesimals ' which it employs is a virtual recognition of System in knowledge or of the principle of Becoming as distinct from that of abstract Being. When we say that a thing (a geometrical figure, for instance) has a certain quality or characteristic in an infinitely small amount, we mean that it both has and has not that quality or characteristic, or (to use another metaphor made familiar by Psycho-physics) that it is on the ' threshold ' of having it. The identity of the thing is not merely superficial, of such a kind that when a quality seems to pass away from it the thing ceases to exist and another thing ap- pears ; the identity of the thing is maintained through an indefinite amount of difference. Thus, as we have seen, the point, the line, the surface, and the solid are all recog- nized as differences or relations within one system. So in general, when we have shown that the difference between STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 83 one thing and another is infinitely little, we have not converted each into the other, but have explained them, both by referring them to a common ground. We can ex- press each in terms of the other, provided we state expli- citly their relations to one another within some system. A parabola is not an ellipse ; but a parabola is an ellipse with one of its foci at an infinite distance from the other. , , Continuity and the Logical Calculus. Now it cannot be said that all this was fully manifest to Leibniz himself ; but the truth of it underlies his thinking. The Infinitesimal Calculus in his mathematics is an expression of th& same tendency of thought which makes the principle of sufficient reason so important an influence in his philosophy — the tendency to a less abstract, less dogmatic, more intensive way of looking at things, in contrast with the a priori deductive methods of the Cartesians. The influence of the mathematics of Leibniz upon his philosophy appears chiefly in connexion with his law of continuity and his prolonged efforts to establish a Logical Calculus. As to the law of continuity it is unnecessary to say more. It is the law of the end- less relativity of things, the principle of system, of in- finite multiplicity in unity, and we have seen that the Infinitesimal Calculus is an application of it1. On the 1 Cf. Lettre a M. Bayle (1687) (G. iii. 51 ; E. 104 a) : 'I have seen the reply of Father Malebranche to the remark I made on some laws of nature which he laid down in the Recherche de la Verite. He appears somewhat disposed to give them up himself, and his in- genuousness is most laudable ; but he gives reasons for it and makes restrictions which would bring us back into the obscurity from which I think I have delivered this subject, and which conflict with a certain principle of general order that I have observed. I hope, therefore, that he will kindly allow me to take this opportunity of explaining this principle, which is of great use in reasoning, and which does not yet appear to be sufficiently employed nor known in all its scope. It has its origin in the conception of the Infinite ; it is absolutely necessary in Geometry, and it also holds good in Physics, inasmuch as the Supreme Wisdom, which is the source of all things, acts as a perfect geometrician, and according to a harmony which cannot be bettered. . . . The principle may be stated thus : When the difference between two cases can be diminished below any G 2 84 INTRODUCTION other hand, the endeavour to find a Logical Calculus (implying a universal philosophical language or system of signs) is an attempt to apply in theological and philo- sophical investigations an analytic method analogous to that which had proved so successful in Geometry and Physics !. It seemed to Leibniz that if all the complex given magnitude in datis or in the antecedents [ce qui est pose] it will neces- sarily also be diminished below every given magnitude in quaesitis or in the consequents [ce qui en resulte]. Or, to put it more simply : when the cases (or wJiat is given] continually approach and are finally lost in one another, the consequences or results (or what is required) must do the same. This again depends upon a more general principle, to wit : datis ordinatis etiam quaesita sunt ordinata. [If there is order in the grounds there will also be order in the consequents.] But, for the under- standing of this, instances are necessary. It is known that the case or supposition of an ellipse may be made to approximate, as much as we like, to the case of a parabola, so that the difference between the ellipse and the parabola may become less than any given differ- ence, provided that one of the foci of the ellipse be made sufficiently distant from the other, for then the radii vectores proceeding from this distant focus will differ from parallel radii vectores as little as we like. Consequently all the geometrical theorems which may be proved of the ellipse in general can be applied to the parabola by considering it as an ellipse one of whose foci is at an infinite distance, or (to avoid this expression) as a figure which differs from some ellipse by less than any given difference. The same principle holds in Physics. For instance, rest may be regarded as an infinitely small velocity or as an infinite slowness. Accordingly, whatever is true of slowness or velocity in general ought also to be true of rest, thus understood ; so that the law of rest should be regarded as a particular ease of the law of motion. Otherwise, if this does not hold, it will be a sure sign that these laws are ill- constructed. In the same way equality may be regarded as an infinitely small inequality, and inequality may be made to approxi- mate to equality as much as we like.' See also New Essays, Intro- duction, p. 376, and Nouveaux Essais, bk. iv. ch. 16, § 12 (E. 392 a ; G. v. 455) : ' But the beauty of nature . . . requires the appearance of discontinuity [sauts~] and, so to speak, musical cadences among phenomena.' In the letter to Bayle above quoted, Leibniz also remarks (E. 106 a ; G. iii. 54) : ' It is true that in compound things a small change may sometimes produce a great effect. For instance, a spark falling upon a large mass of gunpowder might overthrow a whole town ; but that is not contrary to our principle, and might indeed be explained on general principles. But in the case of elements or simple things nothing like this could happen ; otherwise nature would not be the i-esult of infinite wisdom.' 1 As to the analogy between Symbolic Thought and Algebra, &c., cf. Locke, Essay, bk. ii. ch. 29, § 9 (Eraser's ed. vol. i. p. 490). See also Fraser, vol. ii. pp. 12 and 124, where further references will be found. STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 85 and apparently disconnected ideas which make up our knowledge could be analyzed into their simple elements, and if these elements could each be represented by a definite sign, we should have a kind of 'alphabet of human thoughts.' By the combination of these signs (letters of the alphabet of thought) a system of true knowledge would be built up, in which reality would be more and more adequately represented or symbolized. For, according to Leibniz, the progress of knowledge con- sists in passing from obscure to clear ideas, from clear to distinct, from distinct to adequate. Ideas are obscure when analysis has not proceeded so far as to enable us definitely to distinguish them from others. They are clear when we can so distinguish them, but are not yet able to enumerate their particular elements or qualities. They are distinct when we can enumerate their qualities, and they are adequate only when the analysis is complete, that is to say, when all the elements of the clear and distinct idea are themselves clear and distinct. In many cases the analysis may result in an infinite series of elements ; but the principles of the Infinitesimal Calculus in mathe- matics have shown that this does not necessarily render calculation impossible or inaccurate l. Thus it seemed to Leibniz that a synthetic calculus, based upon a thorough analysis, would be the most effective instrument of knowledge that could be devised. ' I feel,' he says, ' that controversies can never be finished, nor silence imposed upon the Sects, unless we give up complicated reasonings in favour of simple calculations, words of vague and un- certain meaning in favour of fixed symbols [characteres]'2.' Thus it will appear that * every paralogism is nothing but an error of calculation.' 'When controversies arise, there will be no more necessity for disputation between two philosophers than between two accountants. Nothing will be needed but that they should take pen in hand, sit 1 Cf. this Introduction, Part ii. p. 61 note. 2 De Scientia Universali sen Calculo Phihsophico (E. 83 b ; G. vii. 200). 86 INTRODUCTION down with their counting-tables, and (having summoned a friend, if they like) say to one another: Let us calculate.' This sounds like the ungrudging optimism of youth ; but Leibniz was optimist enough t9 cherish the hope of it to his life's end. This project of the Logical Calculus or philosophical language connects the mathematics of Leibniz with his theory of knowledge, while the Calculus of Infinitesimals finds immediate application in his revision of Descartes's theories regarding matter and motion. Descartes treated motion and rest synthetically as constant quantitative wholes. Leibniz regards them analytically as consisting of an infinite series of degrees of one constant force. Accordingly Leibniz admits that the Cartesian laws of motion have a certain validity in relation to ' abstract ' motion, but denies that they are adequate to the 'con- crete ' physical phenomena. B. MATTER. Descartes 's Theory of Matter and Motion. As we have already seen, Leibniz's view of matter can be understood only as it appears in contrast with that of Descartes. In accordance with his interpretation of the principle of contradiction, viz. that the essence of a thing consists in that only which is common to all its manifes- tations, or (otherwise expressed) in that only which remains after all varieties or specific determinations have been excluded, Descartes maintained that matter is essen- tially extension. Bodily substance and magnitude or spatial extent are identical. And all the changes in matter or extension are ultimately reducible to motion. Motion is regarded by Descartes as being ' the transference of a portion of matter or a body from the neighbourhood of those bodies which are in direct contact with it, and which we consider as at rest, to the neighbourhood of other bodies or portions of matter V Matter is infinitely 1 Piincipia, Part ii. 25. Descartes adds : ' By a body, or rather STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 87 divisible. Its division is due to motion. Its forms arise solely from the combinations and separations of its parts, which also are due to motion. ' All the variety of matter, or the diversity of its forms, depends on motion1.' 'I frankly avow that I acknowledge in corporeal things no other matter than that which can be divided, shaped [figurees], and moved in all kinds of ways, that is to say, that which mathematicians call quantity, and which they take as the object of their demonstrations ; and in this matter I consider only its divisions, shapes [figures], and motions ; and, in short, regarding this I will accept nothing as true which is not deduced from it with as much certainty as belongs to a mathematical demonstra- tion. And inasmuch as by this means all the phenomena of nature may be explained ... it seems to me that in Physics no other principles ought to be accepted, or even desired, than those which are here expounded V Conservation of Motion (or Momentum), its Direction being left out of account. Again, according to Descartes, the quantity of motion in the world (or in any material system complete in itself and apart fr^m all external influences) is constant. The motion (or momentum), whose quantity is thus con- stant, is in each particular case directly proportional to the mass and the velocity of the moving body, and it may a portion of matter, I mean the whole of what is transferred to- gether, although this may be composed of several parts which themselves have other motions. And I say that motion is the transfr rence and not the force or activity which transfers, in order to show that motion is always in the moving object and not in that which moves it ; for it seems to me that these two things are not usually distinguished with sufficient care. Further, I mean that motion is a property of the moving thing and not a substance ; just as form is a property of the thing which has a form, and rest is a property of that which is at rest.' 1 Principia, Part ii. 23 (Veitch's tr.). 2 Ibid. Part ii. 64 (tr. from Abbe Picot's French). Descartes's object is to show that all the motion in the world is one, and thus to get rid of the later Scholastic theories which referred each parti- cular motion to some unexplained principle in the moving body. 88 INTRODUCTION be expressed by the formula mv. Now no new motion can come to any body from itself ; no material body is self-moved, because its essence is pure extension, and the idea of extension does not necessarily involve the trans- ference of parts. To any quantity of matter, whether large or small, motion comes entirely from without. Thus at the creation of the world the whole material universe received a certain fixed quantity of motion, which is con- served by the * ordinary co-operation ' [concours ordinaire] of God. Motion is thus a positive thing and not merely relative to rest. Motion is not opposed to motion, but to rest. Motions do not cancel one another ; they are quantities which can merely be combined and separated. And, on the other hand, each individual portion of matter must remain in the state in which it is, unless it receives motion from outside itself. The motion of any one body is increased only by a corresponding decrease in the motion of some other ; and the motion of any body is decreased only by a part of it passing into some other. Motion is diffused, but never destroyed \ 1 Cf. Principia, ii. 36 (Veitch's tr.) : ' With respect to the general cause of motion, it seems manifest to me that it is none other than God Himself, who in the beginning created matter along with motion and rest, and now by His ordinary 'concourse' alone pre- serves in the whole the same amount of motion and rest that He then placed in it. For, although motion is nothing in the matter moved but its mode, it has yet a certain and determinate quantity, which we easily understand may remain always the same in the whole universe, although it changes in each of the parts of it. So that, in truth, we may hold when a part of matter is moved with double the quickness of another, and that other is twice the size of the former, that there is just precisely as much motion, but no more, in the less body as in the greater ; and that, in proportion as the motion of any one part is reduced, so is that of some other and equal portion accelerated. We also know that there is perfection in God, not only because He is in Himself immutable, but because He operates in the most constant and immutable manner possible ; so that, with the exception of those mutations which manifest experience or Divine revelation renders certain, and which we per- ceive or believe are brought about without any change in the Creator, we ought to suppose no other in His works, lest there should thence arise ground for concluding inconstancy in God Himself. Whence it follows, as most consonant to reason, that merely because God diversely moved the parts of matter when He STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 89 Now it follows from this, that, while the quantity of motion in the world, or in any isolated system of bodies, is constant, its direction is variable. For, as all space is body and is therefore a plenum, moving bodies must con- tinually impinge upon others ; and if a moving body be supposed to impinge upon a body at rest, of such mass that the moving body is unable to overcome the resistance of the other and to make it move, then the direction of the moving body is changed ; it rebounds in the direction from Which it came or is deflected in some other way. But, as the moving body has been unable to impart any of its motion to the body at rest, the quantity of its motion remains unchanged, while its direction changes — it being, of course, understood that the action of all other bodies, except the two in question, is left out of account 1. Leibniz's Theory of Motion. Conservation of Force. Now, according to Leibniz, motion is simply change of position. It is not a positive quality belonging, for the time being, to the moving body ; but motion and rest are entirely relative to one another. If the relative position of any two bodies changes, we may regard either as moving and the other as at rest 2. And, in general, rest is merely an infinitely small degree of motion ; nothing first created them, and now preserves all that matter, manifestly in the same way and on the same principle o~n which He first created it, He also always preserves the same quantity of motion in the matter itself.' 1 Cf. Principia, ii. 41 : ' Each thing, whatever it is, always con- tinues to be as it is in itself simply, and not as it* is in relation to other things, until it is compelled to change its state by contact with some other thing. From this it necessarily follows that a moving body, which meets on its course another body so firm and impenetrable that it cannot move it in any way, entirely loses the determination it had of moving in this particular direction, and the cause of this is evident, namely, the resistance of the body which prevents it from going further ; but it does not necessarily on this account lose any of its motion, since it is not deprived of its motion by the resisting body or by any other cause, and since motion is not contrary to motion/ 2 Cf. Animadversiones ad Cartes ii Principia (1692?), Part ii. § 25 (G. iv. 369 ; Duncan's tr. p. 60). go INTRODUCTION in the world is absolutely at rest. Accordingly no body begins to move from a state of absolute rest, but from a state which is to be conceived as already one of motion, however small in amount. Actual motion is not some- thing added to a body which, to begin with, is bare mass ; it is always gradual growth or increment of a motion which is already there. Actual motion always pre-sup- poses potential motion or a force which, though it may not be observed, tends to appear as actual motion. Descartes, then, was right in interpreting actual motion as change of position, but wrong in overlooking potential motion and thus in regarding the total quantity of actual apparent motion in the universe, or in any independent system, as constant. He was right also in holding that each body tends to continue in the state in which it is ; but he was wrong in thinking that a body can ever be in a state of absolute rest, and thus in supposing that one motion cannot oppose another, but can only be opposed by rest. As a matter of fact everything tends to move, and would move, were it not for counteracting tendencies to motion in other things 1. That which is conserved, then, is not actual motion, as an extrinsic property of material substance, but this intrinsic tendency or potentiality of motion, which Leibniz calls force. As mere change of position does not enable us to attribute motion to one of the two bodies whose position changes, and not to the other, the body which we call the moving body (as dis- tinct from the body at rest) is so, not in virtue of its motion (in the sense of change of position), but because it 1 Cf. Lettre a M. Pelisson (1691) (Foucher de Careil, i. 208 ; Dutens, i- 733) : ' It must be observed that every body makes an effort to act on outside things, and would perceptibly act if the contrary efforts of surrounding bodies did not prevent it. This has not been sufficiently noticed by our moderns. They imagine that a body might be perfectly at rest, without any effort. But this is due to their failure to understand what bodily substance really is ; for in my opinion substance cannot (at any rate naturally) be without action. This also disproves the inaction which Socinians attribute to dis- embodied souls.' STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 9! contains within itself the cause of the change, the force or activity which produces the motion. ' The notion of force,' says Leibniz, 'is as clear as that of activity and of passivity, for it is that from which activity follows, when nothing prevents it. It is eifort, conatus ; and while motion is a successive thing, which consequently never exists, any more than time, because all its parts never exist together — while, I say, that is so, force or eifort, on the other hand, exists quite completely at every instant and must be something genuine and real. And, as nature has to do rather with the real than with that which does not completely exist except in our mind, it appears (in consequence of what I have shown) that it is the same quantity of force, and not (as Descartes believed) the same quantity of motion, that is preserved in nature V This force, then, which is constant, is not only an actual but a potential reality. It is not mere capacity for motion, mere passive movableness, nor is it actual manifest motion or activity in general. It is something between the two, an undeveloped or restrained tendency to act, which in appropriate circumstances is the producer of action 2. This force is to be measured by the quantity of effect it produces. Descartes rightly insisted on the quantity of effect as the thing to be measured ; but he 1 Lettre a M. Pelisson (no date, probably 1691) (Dutens, i. 719 ; Foucher de Careil, i. 157). ' The relative velocity of two bodies ' [i. e. their apparent motion] ' may remain the same, although the real velocities and absolute forces of the bodies change in an infinity of ways, so that conservation of relative velocity has nothing to do with what is absolute in the bodies.' Essai de dynamique (Gr. Math, vi. 216). Cf. Appendix I, p. 351. 2 Cf. De Primae Philosophiae Emendatione, &c. (1694) (E. 122 b ; G. iv 469) : l Active force differs from the bare potency commonly recog- nized in the Schools. For the active potency of the Scholastics, or faculty, is nothing but a mere possibility of acting, which neverthe- less requires an outer excitation or stimulus, that it may be turned into activity. But active force contains a certain activity [actus] and is a mean between the faculty of acting and action itself. It includes effort and thus passes into operation by itself, requiring no aids, but only the removal of hindrance. This may be illustrated by the example of a heavy hanging body stretching the rope which holds it up, or by that of a drawn bow.' 92 INTRODUCTION conceived the effect in too narrow a way, regarding it merely as actual motion (i. e. the momentum acquired by a body) rather than the work done by the force, the kinetic energy it produces (i.e. the vis viva which the body acquires, and which Leibniz calls action motrice). The formula for this action motrice is not mv but mv*. ' In the uniform motions of one and the same body, (i) the action l of traversing two leagues in two hours is double the action of traversing one league in one hour (for the first action contains the second exactly twice) ; (2) the action of tra- versing one league in one hour is double the action of traversing one league in two hours (or, actions which produce one and the same effect are proportional to their velocities) : therefore (3) the action of traversing two leagues in two hours is four times (quadruple) the action of traversing one league in two hours. This demonstration shows that a moving body which receives a double or triple velocity, in order that it may produce a double or triple effect in one and the same time, receives a quadruple or nonuple action. Thus actions are proportional to the squares of the velocities. But most fortunately this happens to agree with my calculation of force, drawn both from experiments and from the pre- supposition that there is no mechanical perpetual motion. For, according to my calculation, forces are proportional to the heights by descending from which heavy bodies might have obtained their velocities, that is to say, as the squares of the velocities. And, as there is always conserved the total force for re-ascending to the same height or for producing some other effect, it follows that there is conserved also the same quantity of motive " force " [action motrice] in the world ; that is to say, to put it definitely, that in any one hour there is as much action motrice in the universe as there is in any other hour. But at every moment 2 the 1 I. e. the work done or vis viva. For a full explanation of the whole matter, see Stallo, Concepts of Modern Physics, ch. vi, especially pp. 71 sqq. 1 * A momentary state of a body in motion cannot contain motion, STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 93 same quantity of force is conserved. And in fact action is nothing but the exercise of force, and amounts to the product of the force into the time1.' Accordingly this motive force or vis viva, the amount of which is constant, includes direction, as well as quantity, of motion. For the measure of it is height, or position relatively to the surface of the earth. Descartes's l quantity of motion ' (mv) is the effect of a given force regarded merely as acting during a given time. Leibniz's vis viva (mv2) is the effect of a given force regarded also as acting through a given distance. And Descartes did not take account of the direction of motion, because he did not take into con- sideration the distance through which the force acts. Leibniz's Theory of Matter. (i) Materia prima. This doctrine of the conservation of force, as Leibniz conceives it, involves the rejection of the theory that material substance is nothing but extension 2. Extension for motion requires time, but it none the less involves force.' Lettre a Des Maizeaux (1711) (E. 676 a ; G. vii. 534). 1 Lettre a Bayle (undated) (E. 192 a ; G. iii. 60), cf. G. Math, vi. 117. Of course, from one point of view, Leibniz's statement is not quite accurate, since there are many forms .of energy of which it takes no account. It is, however, on right lines. And indeed (as Du Bois-Keymond and Stallo have pointed out) Leibniz in one passage anticipates the modern theory of the transformation of energy (the apparent loss of molar motion being represented by increase of molecular motion), although the idea was not worked out until a much more recent time. ' I had maintained,' says Leibniz, ' that active forces are conserved in the world. It is objected that two soft, or non-elastic bodies, when they collide, lose some of their force. I answer, No. It is true that the "wholes" lose force in respect of their total motion ; but the parts received it, being agitated within the whole by the force of the collision. Thus it is only apparently that the loss occurs. The forces are not destroyed, but dissipated among the particles. That is not losing them but doing as is done by those who turn large money into small change.' Cinquieme Lettre a Clarke, 99 (E. 775 a; G. vii. 414). 2 Projet d'une Lettre a Arnauld (1686) (G. ii. 72) : 'Extension is an attribute which cannot constitute a concrete [accompli'} being. We cannot draw from it any activity or change. It expresses only a present state, and not at all the future and the past, which the notion of a substance ought to express. When two triangles are 94 INTRODUCTION is mere capacity for receiving motion, bare movableness, while motion is complete activity and is entirely extrinsic to that which is moved. Force, on the other hand, is, as we have seen, something between the two, viz. a potentiality f- of motion or action that is always passing into actual action when it is not prevented by a similar tendency in another body. This force, then, shows itself not merely in actual, positive motion, but in hindrance or resistance. And if this force were not of the essence of material bodies there would be no resistance among bodies and the absurdity of perpetual motion would be true. For if material bodies consist solely of extension, and if one such body moving should come into contact with another at rest (i. e. destitute of motion), then the former must carry the latter along with it. For, ex hypothcsi, there is nothing but space to resist the progress of the moving body, and, if motion is possible at all, it must be motion through space, i.e. motion which mere space cannot resist1. Accordingly, in addition to extension (however it may be interpreted), eveiy material body must have resistance or impenetrability. This mere passive resistance Leibniz on various occasions calls avriTviria. The avTirviria of a body is simply its need of space. The body is not mere found joined together, we cannot infer from them how the joining has taken place. For it may have happened in various ways ; but nothing which can have several causes is ever a concrete [accompli] being.' 1 Epistola ad Des Bosses (1706) (G. ii. 295) : 'If, with the Carte- sians, we were to admit a plenum and the uniformity of matter, adding only motion, it would follow that there would never be any- thing in the world but a substitution of equivalents, as if the whole universe were to reduce itself to the motion of a perfectly uniform wheel about its axis or to the revolutions of concentric circles of perfectly homogeneous matter. In that case, it would not be pos- sible, even for an angel, to distinguish the state of the world at one moment from its state at another moment. For there could not be any variety in the phenomena. That is why, in addition to figure, size, and movement, there must be admitted forms from which there arises in matter a variety of appearances ; and I do not see whence we can draw these forms, if they are to be intelligible, except from Entelechies.' Cf. De Ipsa Natura (1693), § 13 (E. 158 b ; G. iv. 512). STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 95 place : but it cannot be a body unless it has a place of its own. And its avriTviria consists in its .maintaining its place, staying where it is. Kesistance is thus a passive force. ' Matter taken by itself or bare matter consists of avTiTwrrta and extension. By avriTwria I mean that attribute in virtue of which matter is in space. Extension is con- tinuation through space, or continuous diffusion through- out a place \ ' Matter is that which consists in di/TiTwria or which resists penetration ; and thus bare matter is merely passive 2. ' In so far, then, as a material body is extended and occupies a place which cannot be occupied by any other body at the same time (for this is the meaning of avrirviria or impenetrability), it consists of bare matter. Bare or abstract matter, as thus denned a + extension), Leibniz usually calls materia prima. (2) Materia secunda. But we must beware of supposing that this materia prima is by itself anything actual. As the mathematical point is nothing actual, but is the indivisible limit of extension, so materia prima is the indivisible limit of matter. No portion of matter, no material body, consists of materia prima alone, just as no portion of extension is a mere mathematical point. For materia prima is simply body considered as if it were purely passive : it is the abstract passivity of body. But, as we have seen, there is, according to Leibniz, no such thing as absolute passivity. Passive resistance, impenetrability, inertia, always involve a real force, a tendency to action, though that tendency may actually be prevented by counteracting forces from realizing itself at this or that particular moment. Passivity is the limit of activity, as rest is the limit of motion. Every material body, then, is ultimately something more than avriTinria + extension. It is essen- tially force or energy, activity of some kind. And 1 De Anima Brutorum (1710), § i (E. 462 a ; G. vii. 328). 2 Epistola ad Bierlingium (1710) (E. 678 a ; G. vii. 501). 96 INTRODUCTION inasmuch as this force is a potential activity, a force which tends to realize itself, it is automatic or sponta- neous, it contains within itself the principle of its future conditions, it is an Entelechy. Thus every actual material body is materia secunda, from which materia prima is merely a mental abstraction \ Every complete substance is materia prima + Entelechy, i. e. passivity + activity. Now while materia prima, being abstract passivity, is not to be regarded as real substance, materia secunda, inasmuch as it is matter and is therefore extended and infinitely divisible, is, on the other hand, not to be confounded with individual substance. Materia secunda must con- tain an entelechy, but is not identical with it. Materia secunda is an aggregate of things : it is to be conceived as quantitative, consisting of paries extra partes, and is thus quite distinct from substance, which must be conceived as striving force, i. e. under the relation of means to end2. 1 Cf. Epistola ad R. C. Wagnerum (1710) (E. 466 a ; G. vii. 529) : 'The active principle is not attributed by me to bare matter or maieria prima, which is merely passive and consists solely in O.VTL- jvrria and extension ; but to body or clothed matter or materia secunda, which contains in addition a primary entelechy or active principle. . . . The resistance of bare matter is not activity, but mere passivity, inasmuch as it has avTirvvta or impenetrability, by which indeed it resists that which would penetrate it. but does not re-act unless it has in addition an elastic force. This elastic force must be derived from motion, and thus also from an active force super- added to matter/ Also De Ipsa Natura (1698), § 12 (E. 158 b ; G. iv. 512) : ' Matter is understood as either materia secunda or materia prima ; materia secunda is indeed a complete substance, but not a merely passive one ; materia prima is merely passive, but is not a complete substance ; and there must further be added to it a soul, or form analogous to a soul, ivrt\cx*ia V "purr), that is a certain effort or primary force of acting, which itself is an indwelling law, imprinted by Divine decree.' It should be noted that the expres- sion 'substance,' as here applied to materia secunda, is not to be taken too strictly. Materia secunda is not so much substantia as sub- stantiata. This is more clearly brought out in Leibniz's later writings. See Monadology, note 2, and this Introduction, Part iii. p. 98 note. " Cf. Lettre a Remand (1715) (E. 736 a; G. iii. 657): 'Strictly speaking, materia prima is not a substance, but something in- complete. And materia secunda (as, for instance, the organic body) is not a substance, but for another reason : namely, because it is STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 97 In short, as materia prima is abstract passivity, the limit of activity, and is thus in reality merely the finitude or imperfection of a Monad, so materia secunda is mere abstract quantity, the limit of intension, and is thus a mere phenomenon of that which is essentially one and indivisible, of the 'soul' which the body 'contains1.' Accordingly every created Monad or simple substance has materia prima in so far as it is not entirely active ; or, in other words (since activity and passivity are relative terms), every created Monad must have materia prima, because its activity is not entirely realized, but is in part potential, because it is not actus purus, activity without passivity. ' Materia prima is essential to every entelechy • and can never be separated from it, since it completes it, *nd is itself the passive potentiality of the whole complete substance. . . . God . . . cannot deprive a substance of materia prima ; for He would thus make it wholly pure activity [purus actus] wThich He Himself alone is'-'.' Materia secunda, on the other hand, is not necessarily attached to any specific entelechy or individual substance. It is a relationship of Monads imperfectly conceived by us as a group of things which may vary from time to time, ^and which, as a matter of fact, is constantly varying. Leibniz compares it to a river 3. i God, by His absolute power, may be able to deprive substance of materia secunda*.' In fact, it is not by itself anything real, but is merely the relation of certain Monads, regarded abstractly as a temporary aggregation or collocation. The only real existences are the Monads, which are purely spiritual, non-spatial existences, but in relatively confused or a collection of several substances, like a pond full of fish, or a flock of sheep ; and consequently it is what is called unum per accidens : in a word, a phenomenon. A real substance (such as an animal) is composed of an immaterial soul an«d an organic body ; and it is the combination of these two that is called unum per se.' 1 Cf. this Introduction, Part iii. pp. 78 sqq. a Epistola ad Des Bosses (1706) (E. 440 b ; G. ii. 324). 3 Ibid. (1706) (E. 436 b ; G. ii. 306). Cf. p. 1 14 and Monadology, § 71. 4 Ibid. (1706) (E. 440 b ; G. ii. 325'). H 98 INTRODUCTION abstract and imperfect thought (i.e. in 'sense' or ' imagination ' as distinct from thought proper) we are presented with the phenomena of things variously grouped in space, and these groups, qua groups, are materia secunda l. Phenomena bene fundata. As materia secunda is always a mere aggregate, while yet every aggregate pre-supposes as its reality an in- divisible simple substance or soul, such aggregates or groups of things, together with their powers, acts, and affections, are sometimes described by Leibniz as well- founded phenomena (phenomena bene fundata). They are 1 Cf. Lettre a Arnauld (1686) (G. ii. 75, 76) : ' In my opinion, our body in itself (setting aside the soul), or the Cadaver, can be called one substance only by a wrong use of terms, like a machine or a heap of stones, which are only beings by aggregation ; for regular or irregular arrangement has nothing to do with unity of sub- stance. ... I hold that a marble pavement is probably only like a heap of stones, and thus cannot pass for only one sub- stance, but is a collection of several. For suppose there are two stones — for example, the diamond of the Grand Duke and that of the Great Mogul — we might give them both, in respect of their value, one and the same collective name, and we might say that they are one pair of diamonds, although they are actually far distant from one another. But it will not be said that these diamonds compose one substance. Now more or less make no difference here. Accordingly, if we bring them nearer one another, and even make them touch one another, they will be none the more united in substance ; and although, after they had been brought into contact, we were to join to them some other body in such a way as to prevent them separating again — for instance, if we were to set them in one ring — all that would make of them only what is called unum per accidens. For it is as by accident that they are compelled to share in the same motion. I hold then that a marble pavement is not one concrete [accomplie~\ substance, any more than would be the water of a pond with all the fish it holds, even although all the water and the fish were frozen together ; or than a flock of sheep, in which the sheep should be supposed to be so bound together that they could only walk in step, and that one could not be touched without all the others crying out. There would be as much difference between a substance and such a being as between a man and a community, like a people, army, society or college, which are moral beings and in which there is something imaginary and created by our mind. Unity of substance requires an indivisible and naturally inde- structible concrete [accomplie~] being, since the notion of such a being includes all that is ever to happen to it.' STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 99 bene fundata in contrast with the phenomena of dreams or visions, which are phenomena pure and simple, not having any proper bond or connexion. Phenomena bene fundata may be distinguished from the phenomena of dreams, inasmuch as the former are vivid, multiplex (i.e. varied in their relations and capable of a variety of tests or observations), and congruous or consistent both with themselves and with the general course of life or experience, which we find in other phenomena. The last of these tests is the most satisfactory, especially when it is supported by the testimony of other people who have also applied it. ' But the most powerful proof of the reality of phenomena (a proof which is, indeed, sufficient by itself) is success in predicting future phenomena from those which are past and present, whether the pre- diction be founded upon the success, so far, of a reason or hypothesis, or upon custom so far observed1.' In short, phenomena bene fundata are distinguished from illusions, inasmuch as they are not merely separate and discon- nected, but held together in a system so that their ante- cedents may be traced and their consequents deduced2. And Leibniz goes so far as to add: — 'Although this entire life were said to be nothing but a dream, and the visible world nothing but a phantasm, I should call this dream or phantasm real enough, if we were never deceived by it, when we use our reason rightly3.' On 1 De Modo distinguendi phenomena realia ab imaginariis (E. 444 a ; G. vii. 320). 2 Can this be reconciled with the view that materia secunda is a mere aggregate or collection ? 3 Loc. cit. Of course it must be remembered that the 'reality' attributed by Leibniz to phenomena bene fundata is entirely relative to the illusoriness of ' pure ' phenomena, such as we have in dreams, and is not to be confounded with the reality of substance. Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. iv. ch. 2, § 14 (E. 344 b ; G. v. 355) : * The truth of the things of sense consists only in the connexion of the phenomena, which must have its reason [ground], and that is what distinguishes them from dreams ; but the truth of our existence and of the cause of phenomena is of another kind, because it establishes substances. . . . The connexion of the pheno- mena which establishes truths of fact in regard to sense-objects H 2 100 INTRODUCTION several occasions Leibniz uses the rainbow as a simile by which to illustrate what he means by a phenomenon bene fundatum1. He simply mentions it without explanation; but we may suppose him to have meant that the rainbow is the type of a phenomenon bene fundatum, inasmuch as. being merely colour, it exists as a rainbow only for those who actually behold it, and is thus a mere appearance, while, being an appearance which results from certain physical conditions of light and moisture, it has a ground or cause, it is the phenomenon of something and is there- fore bene fundatum and not a pure phantasm or illusion. Thus, in general, the qualities of matter, whether secondary, as colour, smell, sound, &c., or primary, as extension, figure, and motion, are phenomena bene fundata. Taken by themselves, as qualities of a matter which has no 'soul,' they are not real but merely subjective. But their order or connexion implies a principle of order (i. e. a soul), and accordingly they are confused (i. e. not fully analyzed) representations, perceptions, or symbols of that which, expressed distinctly, is real substance. Ultimately ( ' metaphysically ' as Leibniz would say) they are reducible to non-spatial perceptions or appetitions of Monads ; but in the form in which they are given to us outside of us is verified by means of truths of reason ; as the pheno- mena of optics are explained by geometry. Yet it must be admitted that this certitude is not of the highest degree. . . . For it is not impossible, metaphysically speaking, that there is a consecu- tive dream lasting as long as the life of a man ; but that is a thing as contrary to reason as would be the fiction that a book could be formed by chance through throwing down type in confusion.' Cf. Locke, Essay, bk. iv. ch. 2, § 14 ; Eraser's ed., vol. ii. pp. 185 sqq., with Prof. Eraser's Notes, and also his Notes on pp. 332 and 333. 1 Cf. Epistola ad Des Bosses (,1715) (E. 728 b ; G. ii. 504) : * I prefer to say that not substances but species' [i.e. sense -qualities] 'remain, and that these are not illusory, like a dream or like a sword pointing towards us out of a concave mirror, or as Dr. Faustus ate a cartful of hay, but true phenomena, that is, in the sense in which a rainbow or a mock sun is a species, indeed as, according to the Cartesians and in truth, colours are species.' Also Epistola ad De Voider (1706) (G. ii. 281, note) : * Extension itself, mass and motion, are no more things than the image in a mirror or the rainbow in a cloud. . . .They exist vo^y rather than P Activity and Passivity of the Monads. Mutual Influence of Substances. Cause and Effect. So far, then, from space being, as Descartes held, the essence of matter, it is a purely ideal relation which we mentally construct between things or phenomena whose ultimate reality or essence is not quantitative, and is consequently not material l. But, as we have seen, every one of the real substances (the Monads), each of which is the essence or reality of a portion of matter, contains that which, taken abstractly, may be described as materia prima. Every created Monad is both active and passive ; for there is no such thing as absolute passivity, and pure activity belongs to God alone. As passive the Monad has materia prima, as jictive it is entelechy. Thus every soul has a body ; there is no such thing as an absolutely disembodied spirit, unless it be the Spirit of God. And, on the other hand, mere soulless body has no real exist- ence: it is an abstraction. The world is active, living through and through, even in its infinitesimal parts. It is compact of souls. Now this activity and passivity of. the Monads do not mean that any Monad exerts a real influence outside of itself or receives any real impression from a substance external to it. The relations between the Monads are purely ideal, and their activity and passivity are altogether internal. As we have seen, a Monad is in itself passive in so far as its perceptions are relatively obscure or confused, active in so far as they are relatively clear and distinct. And similarly, as each Monad perceives or represents the whole universe from its own point of view, one Monad is said to be passive in relation to another in so far as certain perceptions in the former are obscure or confused in com- parison with the corresponding perceptions in the latter ; 1 In spite, however, of this reduction of space, matter, &c., to confused perception, Leibniz continues to use the language of those who speak of them as real, comparing himself to a Copernican who speaks of sunrise. Cp. Theodicee, § 65 (E. 521 a; G. vi. 138). 106 INTRODUCTION while, on the other hand, the Monad whose perceptions are clearer and more distinct is said to be so far active in relation to the other or (ideally, of course) to act upon it \ Thus, as we have already seen, the pre-established harmony is the basis of the inter-relation of the Monads and of their mutual changes 2. Further, as clear and distinct perceptions are simply the unfolding (explication) or explanation of the corresponding more confused per- ceptions, the action of one substance upon another is to be regarded as meaning that the active substance, in so far as it is active, contains within itself (or, simply, is) the explanation of the passive substance, in so far as it is passive. Substances acting upon others are, accordingly, those in which the reason of the changes in the others may be read more distinctly than in those in which the changes actually occur3. Thus the connexion between cause and effect in different substances is a purely ideal relation, a harmony of internal changes and operations, implying no physical influence of one substance upon another. And, further, the cause of any change is not its obscure antecedent nor any power or activity prior in 1 Cf. Spinoza's views of action and passion hi Ethics, Part iii, especially Defs. i and 2, and Props, i, 2, and 3. Also Ethics, Part v. Prop. 40, Corollary. a Cf. p. 40 ; see also Lettre a Arnauld (1690) (G-. ii. 135 ; E. 107 b), in which Leibniz gives a summary of his position : ' There must be everywhere in body substances indivisible, unborn and imperish- able, having something corresponding to souls. . . . Each of these substances contains in its own nature " legem continuationis seriei suarum operationum " [the principle of succession of the series of its own operations] and all that has happened and shall happen to .it. All its actions come from its own inner being [fonds], except Its dependence upon God. Each substance expresses the entire universe, but one does so more distinctly than another, and each expresses it more especially with regard to certain things and according to its own point of view. The_union of soul with body, and indeed the operation of one substance upon another, consists only in the perfect mutual accord of substances, definitely estab- lished through the order of their first creation, in virtue of which each substance, following its own laws, agrees with the rest, meeting their demands ; and the operations of the one thus follow or accompany the operations or change of the other.' 3 Cf. Monadology, §§49 sqq. STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 107 time to the effect ; the true cause is always the reason or explanation, the distinct as opposed to the confused per- ception, whatever may be the time-order of the events or phenomena \ Mechanical and final Causes. Soul and Body. Every substance, as we have seen, consists of soul and body. And the soul, being on the one hand the relatively distinct perception of the substance, and on the other hand its activity, is the final cause of the substance, the end for which it is, the self-development of its nature. It must be conceived under the notion of Becoming, as ^p a thing whose essence it is to move towards an end. It cannot, therefore, be adequately described by purely mechanical conceptions. It has something more than a static self-identity ; its unity unfolds itself in the series of its changes. Its reality is thus not determined merely V by the principle of contradiction, taken as a principle of ->£- pure or abstract self- consistency. The body of every J substance, on the other hand, i. e. its matter, its confused perception, its passivity, is the physical or mechanical cause of the substance. Being entirely abstract, and in itself a bare possibility, body may by itself be adequately described by mechanical conceptions, under the principle of contradiction. Thus we may have an abstract science of physics by which the phenomena of abstract matter are explained on purely mechanical principles, that is, as a system of physical or efficient causes. But if we would explain the concrete reality even of material substance we must employ dynamical rather than mechanical concep- tions, or, in other words, we must regard the world as ultimately and essentially a system of final causes, a system which is the expression, not of an indifferent all- powerful Will, but of an all-powerful Will which knows and decrees the best 2. - 1 See Appendix C, p. 204. 2 Of. Epistola ad Bierlingium (1711) (E. 677 b ; G. vii. 501) : 'You 108 INTRODUCTION C. ORGANISM. Organic and inorganic Bodies. Simple and compound Substances. Dominant Monad. The notion of body existing by itself and that of soul existing by itself are results of confused or imperfect ask about spiritual, or rather incorporeal things, and you say that we see the mechanical arrangement of the parts but not the principles of the mechanism. True ; but, when we see motion also, we understand from this [what we see] the cause of motion, or force. The source of mechanism is primary force [vis primitiva], but the laws of motion, according to which impulses [impetus'} or derivative forces arise out of the primary force, issue from the perception of good and evil, or from that which is most fitting. Thus it is that efficient causes are dependent upon final causes, and spiritual things are in their nature prior to material things, as also they are to us prior in knowledge, because we perceive more immediately [interius] the mind (as it is nearest to us) than the body ; and this indeed Plato and Descartes have observed.' Also Lettre a Remond (1714) (E. 702 a ; G. iii. 607): 4 1 have found that most of the philosophical sects are right in a good part of what they maintain, but not to 'the same extent in what they deny. The Formalists, such as the Platonists and Aristotelians, are right in seeking the source of things in final and formal causes. But they err in neglecting efficient and material causes and in inferring (as did Mr. Henry More in England, and some other Platonists) that there are phenomena which cannot be explained on mechanical principles. But, on the other hand, the Materialists, or those who hold exclusively to the mechanical philosophy, err in setting aside metaphysical considerations and in trying to explain everything by that which is dependent on the imagination. I flatter myself that I have discovered the harmony of the different systems and have seen that both sides are right, provided they do not clash with one another ; that in the phenomena of nature everything happens mechanically and at the same time metaphysically, but that the source of the mechanical is in the metaphysical.' Also Lettre a Arnauld (1686) (G. ii. 77) : * We are obliged to admit many things of which our knowledge is not sufficiently clear and distinct. I hold that the knowledge of extension is very much less so' [than that of substantial Forms, of which he has been speaking], ' witness the remarkable difficulties as to the composition of the continuous ; and it may even be said that bodies have no definite and precise shape, because of the actual sub-division of their parts [i. e. their sub-division ad infinitum]. So that bodies would without doubt be something merely imaginary and apparent if there were nothing but matter and its modifications. Yet it is of no use to mention the unity, notion, or substantial Form of bodies, when we are explaining the particular phenomena of nature, as it is of no use for mathe- STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 109 perception. The world consists solely of Monads, each of which is a concrete unity of soul and body, of entelechy and materia prima. Thus nature is throughout living ; there is nothing really inorganic \ What, then, is meant by the common distinction between organic or living and inorganic or material bodies? In order to answer this question, we must consider more fully the nature of compound substance. While the simple substances alone are real they appear as phenomena in groups or aggregates, which we call compound substances. Indeed, although in reality they are secondary, compound substances are prior to simple substances in the order of knowledge. As phenomena they can be perceived by the senses, while the Monad* cannot be so perceived. For the Monads are not really grouped or combined ; the aggregation is purely pheno- menal. Now each Monad implied in any such aggregate perceives or represents all the phenomena constituting its group, since it perceives the whole universe, of which they are parts. But as each Monad diifers from all the others in the degree of distinctness of its perceptions there must in each group be one Monad which represents the group more distinctly than does any other Monad implied in it. This Monad of most distinct perception in each compound substance Leibniz calls the dominant Monad of the substance 2. It has a formal superiority over the others maticians to investigate the difficulties de compositione continm when they are working at the solution of some problem. These things are none the less important and worthy of consideration in their own place. All the phenomena of bodies can be explained mechanically or by the corpuscular philosophy, according to certain principles of mechanics, which are laid down without taking into consideration whether there are souls or not ; but in an ultimate analysis of the principles of physics, and even of mechanics, it appears that we cannot explain these principles by modifications of extension alone, and the nature of force already requires some- thing else.' See also Antibarbarus Physicus, &c. (after 1687) (Or. vii. 343;. For Leibniz's account of (he development of his views, see Ultimate Origination of Things, Appendix, p. 351. 1 Cf. Monadology, §§63 sqq. 2 Cf . ibid. § 70 ; Principles of Nature and of Grace, § 3. 110 INTRODUCTION implied in the group, though all are really independent, Its control or dominance consists solely in the distinctness of its perceptions. Just as cause is not a real influence of one substance upon another, but merely the relation of activity in the one to corresponding passivity in the other, or of distinct to confused perception, so the central Monad of any compound substance has no physical con- trol over the others, but is dominant because of its activity and distinctness. Thus the relation between the dominant Monad and the phenomena (implying other Monads) which, along with it, constitute a compound substance is similar to the relation between the two elements, active and passive (entelechy and materia prima), which together constitute simple substance or the indi- vidual Monad. The dominant Monad is the entelechy or soul of the compound substance, while its body is a phenomenal aggregate, every portion of which in turn implies a Monad or soul. But this aggregate is materia secunda ; and thus we have simple substance consisting of materia prima and entelechy, and compound substance consisting of materia secunda and dominant Monad. While observing this analogy, we must not forget the essential difference between simple and compound sub- stance. The former alone is really substance : the latter, in so far as it differs from the former, is merely sub- stance by courtesy or common usage. Simple substance is a concrete unity ; compound substance, in so far as it is compound (i. e. apart from its soul or dominant Monad, which is non-quantitative, and therefore cannot be an element in a compound), is merely an aggregate. Thus the materia prima or passivity of the individual Monad is a name for its confused, undeveloped or implicit nature • taken abstractly : it is confused perception in the sub- stance itself. But the materia secunda or body of the compound substance is not confused perception in the substance itself, for the body as compound has no perception of its own, as distinct from the perceptions STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ^ PHILOSOPHY III of the simple substances which it implies. Materia secunda, then, is due to the confused perceptions of those who observe the compound substances. Thus to the eye of God there can be no materia secunda, no com- pound substance ; for in Him there is no confused percep- tion. The aggregates of phenomena which we call things or extended bodies are thus the result of confused percep- tion. And the differences amongst them, which we describe by the names of organic, inorganic, &c., are really differences in their dominant Monads. Without a dominant Monad, body would be mere indeterminate quantity, 'without form' if not 'void,' a chaos of pure difference. The dominant Monad is the unity implied in a* specific or definite aggregate, the unity in virtue of which an aggregate or compound is one thing as distinct from other things. If the dominant Monad be a bare Monad, with unconscious perceptions, we call the body inorganic. If the degree of distinctness in the perceptions of the dominant Monad be a little higher, we call the body a plant and so on. The organic and the inorganic pass imperceptibly into one another, and the degree of organic unity possessed by any body is nothing but the degree of distinctness in the perceptions of its dominant Monad. Thus the parts of an organism are more closely connected, more firmly held together, than those of an inorganic mass, because the dominance of the central Monad is greater, more complete (that is to say, its per- ception is more distinct), in the case of the former than in the case of the latter. Body without soul, or mere matter considered as inor- ganic, that is to say, as an aggregate of parts which have no unity other than their aggregation, is unreal. We may regard it either as an abstraction from concrete substance or (more nearly in Leibniz's way of thinking) as an imperfect perception or representation of concrete substance. Nature is organic throughout : no real thing 112 INTRODUCTION is completely inorganic : what we call ' inorganic ' is really organic in a low degree *. The body of every created substance is the point of view of its soul. As there is no vacuum in nature, the changes in any one body affect every other. Thus in every body the whole world is represented or expressed. But in each dominant Monad, or soul, the aggregate forming its particular body is more distinctly represented than the rest of the world. Thus each soul perceives or represents the universe through the medium of its own body. While it does represent the whole, it represents it in a form in which its own body is more distinct than any other2. The body is like a special lens through which the soul sees the universe. This, of course, fol- lows from the view that body in general is relatively confused perception. For each substance represents the universe 'from its own point of view,' and its point of view is simply the degree of confusedness (or of distinct- ness, for they are entirely relative) of its perceptions 3. 1 Cf. Antibarlarus Physicus, &c. (G-. vii. 344) : ' But indeed, although all bodies are not organic, nevertheless in all bodies, including the inorganic, organic bodies lie hid, so that every mass which to outward appearance is formless [rudts] and quite undif- ferentiated [similaris\ is inwardly not undifferentiated but diver- sified, and yet its variety is not confused but orderly. Thus there is everywhere organism, nowhere chaos, which would be unbe- coming a wise Creator.' * Monadology, § 62; cf. Spinoza, Ethics, Part ii. Props. 12, 13 (Scholium), 16 (Coroll. i\ 26, &c. 3 Yet it must not be supposed that the soul has perfect knowledge of all that takes place in its own body. Cf. Lettre ii Arnauld (1687) (GK ii. 90) : ' It does not follow that the soul must be perfectly conscious [s'apercevoir'] of what happens in the parts of its body, since there are degrees of relationship between these parts them- selves which are not all expressed equally, any more than external things are. The distance of the latter is balanced by the smallness or other disadvantages of the former, and Thales sees the stars when he does not see the ditch before his feet.' Also Lettre a Arnauld (1687) (G. ii. 112) : « In natural perception and in feeling, it is enough that what is divisible and material, and is actually divided among several beings, should be expressed or represented in one indivisible being or in substance which possesses a genuine unity. We cannot doubt the possibility of such a representation of several things in one only, since our soul gives us an instance STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 113 Changes in compound Substances. Development and Envelopment. Every compound substance is in constant change. No created Monad, as we have seenr. can- ever be entirely at rest: each, in virtue of its appetition, is continually either unfolding (developing) itself (i. e. passing from confused to more distinct perception), or enfolding (en- veloping) itself (i. e. passing from distinct to more con- fused perception). And thus, as the dominance of any dominant Monad consists solely in the degree of distinct- ness of its perception, the relations of formal dominance and subordination, which constitute a compound sub- stance, must be continually varying in particular cases. of it. But this representation is .accompanied in the rational soul by consciousness, and then it is called thought. Now this expres- sion occurs everywhere, because all substances are in sympathy with one another, and each receives some proportional change, corresponding to the least change which happens anywhere in the universe, though this change is more or less observable, according as other bodies or their actions have more or less relation to ours. And I think that M. Descartes himself would have admitted this, for he would doubtless allow that, because of the continuity and divisibility of all matter, the least motion has its effect upon neighbouring bodies, and consequently upon one body after another ad infinitum, the effect proportionally diminishing. Thus our body must be in some way affected by the changes in all others. Now to all the motions of our body there correspond certain more or less confused perceptions or thoughts of our soul. Hence the soul also will have some thought of all the motions in the universe, and, in my opinion, every other soul or substance will have some percep- tion or expression of them. It is true that we are not distinctly conscious of all the motions of our body, as, for instance, that of the lymph ; but this may be compared with the fact that I must have some perception of the motion of each wave on the shore, in order that I may be conscious [apercevoir] of that which results from the totality of them, namely the great noise that I hear when close to the sea. Thus also we experience some confused result of all the motions which take place in us ; but being accustomed to this internal motion, we are not distinctly and reflectively conscious of it, except when there is a considerable change in it, as at the beginning of an illness. . . . Now since we are conscious of other bodies only through the relation they have to our own, I was right in saying that the soul expresses best what belongs to our own body. Thus we know the satellites of Saturn or of Jupiter, only in consequence of a motion which takes place in our eyes.' Cf. Spinoza, Ethics, Part ii. props. 24 and 27. 114 INTRODUCTION The phenomena which make up the body of a compound substance must be continually changing according as the dominant Monad rises or falls in perceptive rank. No dominant Monad has a changeless body ; because of its own variations its body 'is in a perpetual flux like a river, and parts are entering into it and passing out of it continually V And there is endless room for variation ; because each compound substance is made up of other compound substances (each with its dominant Monad), and these again are made up of others ad infinitum*. Thus some or all of the things which at one time form an inorganic body may, in new relations, become parts of an organic body and vice versa. And the size of any- body, belonging to a particular dominant Monad, may increase or decrease indefinitely. Metamorphosis. Birth and Death. Accordingly the change in compound substance of every kind is always metamorphosis rather than metem- psychosis3. The fundamental element in every com- pound substance is the dominant Monad, and the matter or body of the substance is continually changing by a gradual removal and addition of parts. It is the body which bit by bit transfers itself from one soul to another. There is no such thing as the sudden transference of a soul from one body to another entirely new body. Such a transference would involve a sudden or discon- tinuous change in the soul itself, which is impossible. 1 Monadology, § 71. So Lotze compares the life of the parts to a throng of travellers. Microcosmus, bk. iii. ch. 4, § 4 (Eng Tr, vol. i. p. 368). 2 Cf. Epistola ad BernouUium (1698) (G-. Math. iii. 560 1 : « I would readily allow that there are animals (in the ordinary sense) in- comparably greater than ours ; and I have sometimes said in jest that there may be some system similar to ours, which is the watch of a very great giant/ Also Monadology, §§66 sqq. ; cf. Spinoza, Ethics, Part ii. Lemma vii. Scholium. 3 Cf. EpistoUi ad Bemoullium (1698) (G. Math. iii. 561) : LXavOpu7ria.) will, if I mistake not, be most fittingly defined as the charity of a wise man, that is to say, charity in obedience to the dictates of wisdom. . . . Charity is 1 Cf. On the Notions of Right and Justice, p. 285 (E. 118 b). STATEMENT OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 149 universal benevolence, and benevolence is the habit of loving1.' Thus the ethical progress of man is an approach to the reality that is in God, a bringing forth of the image of God which is hidden in the soul, through growing en- lightenment, that is to say, through the appetition of the soul passing forward to ever clearer and more distinct perceptions. This feature of the philosophy of Leibniz leads Windelband to describe his ethics as expressing 1 the philanthropic ideal of morality which was character- istic of the AufTdarung period ' in Germany. i " Enlighten thyself, and have a care for the enlightenment of thy fel- lows : so shall you all be happy ; " that is the philosophy professed by the whole eighteenth century in Germany2.' 1 On the Notions of Right and Justice (1693), p. 283 (E. 118 a). Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. ii. ch. 28, § 5 (E. 286 b ; G. v. 232) : ' Ac- cording to this notion' [externally imposed law], 'one and the same action would be at the same time morally good or morally bad, under different legislators, just as our able author' [Locke] ' considered virtue as that which is praised, and accordingly one and the same action would be virtuous or not, according to the different opinions of men. Now, as that is not the meaning that is usually given to morally good and virtuous actions, I should prefer for my part to take as the measure of moral good and virtue the invariable rule of reason, which it is the office of God to maintain. So we may be assured that by His means, every moral good becomes also a physical good, or as the ancients said, every honourable act is useful ; in place of which, if we would express the view of our author, we should have to say that moral good or evil is an imposed or ordained [institutif^ good or evil, which he who has command of power endeavours by rewards or penalties to make us do or shun. The good thing is, that what proceeds from the general ordinance of God is conformable to nature or to reason/ 2 Windelband, Geschichte der neueren Philosophie, vol. i. p. 477. Cf. Von der Gluckseligkeit (E. 673 a ; G. vii. 89) : ' If now a noble \hohe] person attains to this, that in the midst of all luxury and honours he yet finds his greatest enjoyment in the activities of his under- standing and the practice of virtue, then I hold him doubly noble : in himself, on account of this happiness and true joy of his ; and for others, since it is most certain that this person, on account of his power and insight, can and will also impart light and virtue to many others, for such an imparting means a reflected light upon the giver, and those who have the same common aim can help one another and give new light in the investigation of truth, the increase of human powers, and the promotion of that which is best for all. Thus the exalted \hohe~] happiness of noble \hohe~] 150 INTRODUCTION and also enlightened persons appears from this that they can do as much for their happiness as if they had a thousand hands and a thousand lives, indeed as if they were to live a thousand times as long as they do. For our life is to be counted a true life in so far as we do good in it. Now he who does much good in a shorter time is the same as him who lives a thousand times longer; which is the case with those who can get a thousand and more than a thousand hands to work along with them, and consequently in a few years more good can happen for their highest peace and enjoyment than otherwise many centuries could bring to pass.' PART IV. HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL ESTIMATE OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF LEIBNIZ. Relation of Leibniz to earlier Thinking, especially to the Peripatetic and Atomist Positions. No genuine thinker can set himself outside of the philosophic succession. However protestant or revolu- tionary he may be, his problem is always to a great extent determined for him by the systems of the past. Unless intellect is to be called ' bloodless ' these systems may be said to be in his blood ; he could not turn against them if they were not in him, if he had not made them his own. He may cease to seek for truth in the perplexing world, and try to find it in what he takes to be the simplicity and certainty of his own nature ; but, whether he knows it or not, that very nature of his is to a great extent what the tiresome world has made it. He may ignore history or scorn it, but he cannot escape from it. The conviction of some such truth as this was very strong in Leibniz. He held it against the fashion of his time. The early part of the seventeenth century was a time when the new felt itself to be so very new, the modern so very modern, that, with the infallibility of youth, it could aiford to despise what seemed ancient, worn-out, and superseded. When ' our moderns ' (as Leibniz frequently calls them) were not contemptuous of older thought they were unconscious of it. In fact, history for them meant a blind tradition, which they had 152 INTRODUCTION cast off. Descartes, for instance, when he turned from courts and camps to meditation by his own fireside, professed to renounce entirely the methods and results of earlier thinkers, and to draw from his own unaided con- sciousness a system of truth which no learned sophistry could shake. Descartes was the discoverer of the ' plain man.' Unsophisticated mother-wit will of itself produce absolutely certain knowledge, if only we put the right instrument into its hands, or in other words, if we suggest to it a right method l. Thinking thus, Descartes 1 Cf. Recherche de la Verite par les Lumieres Naturelles, (Euvres de Descartes (Cousin), vol. xi. p. 334 : ' My purpose in this work is to bring to light the wealth of our nature, by throwing open to every one the way by which he may find in himself, without borrowing anything from anybody else, the knowledge that is necessary for the conduct of his life, and by which he may afterwards make use of this knowledge to master the most abstruse sciences to which human reason can attain. But lest the magnitude of my plan should at once fill your mind with such amazement that you can no longer find it possible to have any confidence in what I say, I may tell you that what I am undertaking is not so difficult as might be imagined. In fact, the branches of knowledge which are not beyond the reach of the human mind are united together by so wonderful a bond and can be deduced from one another with so complete a necessity, that not much art and skill are required to find them out, provided we begin with the most simple and learn to rise gradually to the most exalted. This I intend to show here, by means of a succession of reasonings so clear and so commonplace that every one will see that, if he has not noticed the same things as I have, it is only because he has not turned his eyes in the right direction nor given his thoughts to the same objects as I have, and that I no more deserve glory for having discovered these things than would a peasant deserve it for having found by chance under his feet a treasure which had long remained hidden, though diligently sought after. ... I will not inquire into what others have known or have not known. Suffice it to observe that, although all the knowledge we can desire were to be found in books, yet the good they contain is mixed up with so much that is useless and is scattered throughout so many big volumes that life is not long enough to read them, and to recognize what is useful in them would require more ability than to find it out for our- selves. So I hope the reader will not be displeased to find here a shorter way, and that the truths I bring forward will be accept- able to him, although I do not borrow them from Plato or Aristotle but offer them as having value in themselves, like money which has the same worth whether it comes from a peasant's purse or from the treasury.' Cf. Discourse on Method, Part vi. (Veitch's Translation, pp. 109 et sqq.). Huet says that 'though Descartes ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 153 inevitably turned his back upon the history of thought, counting it little better than ' old wives' fables1.' In Leibniz, on the other hand, there is a double re- action— a reaction against the scorn 'of history, and a reaction against the extremes to which modern philosophy had been carried in its opposition to Scholasticism, The whole bent of Leibniz's thought was against sharp and absolute divisions. Thought does not proceed per saltum. In the history of thinking, as in all other history, i the present is laden with the past and full of the future2.' Thus, for Leibniz, the Scholastics may have been wrong, but they were not absolutely wrong. And the moderns may be right, but they are not entirely right. Nothing in the past is to be completely set at naught, for out of the past the present has come. The one cannot be had carefully studied the ancient philosophers and several of the moderns, he yet affected to appear ignorant of them, in order that he might be regarded as the sole discoverer of his doctrine. In this several of his disciples have too thoroughly followed his example ; for they have imitated his feigned ignorance by culti- vating a real ignorance.' Traite philosophique de la faiblesse de I' Esprit humain, bk. iii. ch. 10. Voltaire also gives point to the general opinion regarding Descartes by the satirical suggestion that Descartes had 'never read anything, not even the Gospels.' Les Systemes, line 37 ; (Euvres Completes, vol. x. p. 169. 1 It was not only the fact of a revolution in thought that gave rise to the Cartesian disregard of history : the very nature of the revolution itself contributed to this end. The substitution of a mechanical for an a priori dogmatic way of explaining things was inevitably connected with a fresh interest in the study of mathematics, and this led to a preference of mathematical to historical methods in philosophy. Cf. Regies pour la Direction de I' Esprit, (Euvres de Descartes (Cousin), vol. xi. p. 211: 'We shall never be mathematicians, even although we were to know by heart all the demonstrations of other people, if we are not capable of solving by ourselves all kinds of problems. In the same way. though we have read all the reasonings of Plato and Aristotle, that will not make us philosophers if we cannot bring to any question a steady judgment. In such a case we should, indeed, have learned not a science, but history.' Also, p. 209 : ' Eegarding the object of our study we must inquire, not what others have thought nor what we ourselves surmise, but what we can see clearly and manifestly [avec evidence], or what we can deduce with certainty. This is the only way to obtain real knowledge [la science'].' 2 Cf. Wallace, Logic of Hegel (2nd ed.) ; Prolegomena, pp. 203 sqq. 154 INTRODUCTION understood without the other. Leibniz from his earliest days had been a vast reader of books, and his erudition tempered his imaginative optimism with reverence and caution. Thus his philosophizing most often takes the form of hypothesis or suggestion rather than that of dogma or demonstration. In the Kantian sense his philosophy is, of course, * dogmatic ' and not ' critical ' ; but to some extent he foreshadows the ' critical spirit V As a thinker, he counts as foreign to him nothing that men have thought, and his ideal philosophy would be a philosophy which says clearly all that all previous thinkers have stammeringly tried to say. So people have called him an 'eclectic,' and possibly his fame has suifered from the imputation. But there is no lack of originality in the * metaphysical romance 2 ' he brings us, for he is to be called an eclectic mainly in contrast with the Cartesian extremists, who repudiated all obligation to the past. While convinced of the value of his own hypotheses, Leibniz rather glories in his indebtedness, rejoicing to find himself in the philosophic succession. 'I despise almost nothing,' he says, 'except judicial astrology and trickeries of that kind3.' 'It happens somehow that the thoughts of other people are usually not displeasing to me, and I appreciate them all, though in divers degrees4.' ' There is as much or more reason to beware of those who, most often through ambition, claim to put forth something new as to mistrust old impressions. And after having devoted a great deal of thought both to the old and the new, I have come to the conclusion that most of the received doctrines can be taken in a right sense. So that 1 'In Leibniz the dogmatic philosophy comes in all points so near to the critical that only one step is needed to rise from the point of view of the one to that of the other.' K. Fischer, Gesch. d. neueren Phil., vol. ii. ch. 21, § i. 2 Hegel, Gesch. d. Philosophic, vol. iii. p. 408. Kant also speaks of the universe of Leibniz as 'a kind of enchanted world' [eine Art von bezauberter Welt]. Rosenkranz, i. 521 ; Hartenstein, iii. 445. 3 Lettre a Bourguet (1714), (G. iii. 562). 4 Specimen Dynamicum (1695) (G. Math. vi. 236). ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 155 I wish clever men would seek to satisfy their ambition rather by building and making progress than by going back and destroying1.' 'This system' [Leibniz's own] ' appears to combine Plato with Democritus, Aristotle with Descartes, the Scholastics with the moderns, theology and ethics with reason. It seems to take the best from all sides, and then to go further than any one has yet gone. ... I see now what Plato meant when he regarded matter as an imperfect and transitory thing ; what Aris- totle intended by his entelechy; what is that promise of another life, which Democritus himself made, accord- ing to Pliny ; how far the Sceptics were right in crying out against the senses ; how animals are automata, as Descartes says, and have nevertheless souls and feeling, as people think ; how a rational explanation is to be given of the views of those who attribute life and perception to all things — such people as Cardan, Campanella, and (better than these) the late Countess of Conway (a Platonist), and our friend, the late M. Francois Mercure Van Helmont (though otherwise bristling with unintelligible paradoxes), with his friend, the late Mr. Henry More V 1 Nouveaux Essais, bk. i. ch. 2, § 21 (E. 219 a ; Gr. v. 92). z Ibid. bk. i. ch. i (E. 205 a ; G. v. 64). Leibniz might have added the name of Spinoza, who says that ' all individual bodies are animate, though in different degrees.' Ethics, Pt. ii. prop. 13, Scholium. Cf. Lettre a Basnage (1698) (E. 153 b ; G. iv. 523) : « When we penetrate deeply into things, we observe more reason than would be believed in most of the sects of the philosophers. The lack of reality in the things of sense, according to the Sceptics ; the Pythagorean and Platonist reduction of everything to har- monies, numbers, ideas, and perceptions; the "One" and even the one Whole of Parmenides and Plotinus, without any Spinozism ; the Stoic connexion, compatible with the spontaneity of others ; the vital philosophy of the Cabbalists and Hermetics, who attri- bute feeling to everything ; the forms and entelechies of Aristotle and the Scholastics ; and on the other hand the mechanical explanation of all particular phenomena, according to Democritus and the moderns— these are all combined together as in a centre of perspective, viewed from which the object (confused from every other point of view) reveals its regularity and the harmony of its parts. We have failed to accomplish this by our sectarian spirit, limiting ourselves by rejecting others.' The writings of Leibniz are full of similar passages. 156 INTRODUCTION Descartes himself * took a good part of his best thoughts ' from the men of old l. And thus, Leibniz would say, it is better frankly to own our obligations and to go back to the past that we may, if possible, draw from it neglected truths, by the aid of which our present theories may be improved and thinking may go forward. For the idea of progress on the basis of history controls the mind of Leibniz, to whatever objects he directs his think- ing2. Accordingly, admitting the value of the modern mechanical philosophy, and yet being conscious of its imperfections and dissatisfied with some of its results, Leibniz turns back to Scholasticism and its roots in the philosophy of Greece, to ' recover the gold from the mire, ' and so build up a more perfect system 3. Thus Dillmann rightly contends that Leibniz can be properly understood only if we recognize that his main endeavour is to reconcile the modern mechanical view of things with the ancient doctrine of 'substantial forms.' Yet it must not be forgotten that Leibniz sought to effect this recon- ciliation by modifying and reconstructing, and not by merely dovetailing one system into another. The way of explaining phenomena by reference to * substantial forms,' which Descartes and Gassendi rejected in favour of a mechanical explanation of nature, was a growth of the Peripatetic philosophy, which in course of time had run to seed. It sprang originally from the sound Aristotelian idea that all events or particular things are to be explained by reference to active principles, not 1 Lettre a Nicaise (1692) (E. 120 a ; G. ii. 534). Cf. De stilo philoso- phico Nizolii (1670), § 24 (E. 67 a ; G. iv. 154). 2 Thus one of his latest (and not least able) expositors, E. Dill- mann, offers Leibniz a homage which he himself would at once have condemned. For Dillmann regards the philosophy of Leibniz as final and all-sufficient, if only it be rightly understood. ' The Monadology is the most perfect fruit of philosophical reflexion, the most complete and brilliant system in the history of philo- sophy.' (Neue DarsteUung, &c., p. 525.) There is a strange irony in the fact that so able and devoted a disciple has so completely missed his master's spirit. 3 Lettre a Remond (1714) (E. 704 b ; G. iii. 625). ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 157 entirely external to the events or things, but appearing in them. But the meaning, the spirit of Aristotle's method was lost sight of. 'Find a principle, a form, of any kind,' came to be the rule of explanation. And thus the number of 'substantial forms' or principles of substance was multiplied indefinitely, while, in addition, the most minute changes in substances were each explained by reference to some ' accidental form ' or principle of accident. Anything sufficed as an explanation so long as it was called a form. Thus when no intelligible account of a phenomenon could readily be given it was attributed to some hidden principle (qualitas occulta), which was described by the name of the phenomenon to be explained. Thus, for instance, Toletus * gives us the valuable information that ' the substantial form of fire is an active principle by which fire, with heat as its instru- ment, produces fire.' After making this amazing state- ment he recollects that fire is sometimes produced by things other than fire, and he proceeds with grave elaboration to prove that 'fire can result from all the substantial forms capable of producing it in air, in water, or in anything else. ' This may be the redudio ad absurdum of the Peripatetic Scholasticism ; for indeed petitio principii could no farther go. It is almost worse than the virtus dormitiva of Moliere's satire. But the author does not appear to have seen the humour of it. Can we wonder, then, that Descartes turned his back upon history ? To him it seemed that an explanation to be an explanation must at least be intelligible. There can be truth and certainty, he thought, only where there is clearness and distinctness. Accordingly all these hidden principles and inexplicable forms must be thrown aside as philosophical lumber, a screen of ignorance and a source of confusion. In true explanation there must be no obscurities, fancies, or 1 Francisco de Toledo (1532-1596), a Spanish cardinal and theo- logian, author of Summa Casuum Conscientiae. 158 INTRODUCTION guesses ; but it must consist in tracing the necessary connexions of things or finding definitely measurable relations between them — connexions and relations which the understanding can clearly grasp. That is, in brief, the mechanical view of what explanation ought to be, as the Cartesians held it in opposition to the Scholastics. Now Leibniz, as we have seen, is not so exclusively enamoured of the clear and distinct as Descartes was. He thinks Descartes has gone too far in the zeal of his reformation. Doubtless the Scholastics were guilty of gross absurdities, but if we are to be satisfied with no explanation which is not absolutely perfect in its intelli- gibility, we shall have to do without explanations of most things, and our science will perforce be very abstract and very limited. For to be perfectly intelligible or clear and distinct in the Cartesian sense, an explanation must either be a self-evident truth or must be logically reducible to such a truth. And Leibniz maintains that, while ideas or abstractions (' possible ' things) may be capable of such explanation as this, it is impossible so thoroughly to explain any actually existing finite thing or phenomenon. We may ' clearly and distinctly ' explain how such a thing is possible ; we cannot * clearly and distinctly ' explain why it exists. No absolute reason can be given for its existence ; we must be content with a sufficient reason. An examination of the measurable relations or connexions of things does not yield an exhaustive account of their nature, and accordingly, while such an exam- ination is valuable so far as it goes, it requires to be supplemented by other considerations. The infinite complexity of things makes a perfect analysis impossible, and consequently, if we confine ourselves to a strictly mathematical method, our science must remain a science of abstractions and not of actual things as they exist. Leibniz, then, admits the value of the mechanical view as regards phenomena, considered in abstraction from the realities of which they are the phenomena, but he returns ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 159 to the older philosophy for an explanation of the realities themselves. Descartes has done well in clearing away the great mass of forms, which explained nothing, and in accounting for all the changes in nature by regarding them as due to variations in the distribution of one constant quantity of motion. But motion is not a deep enough principle to explain reality. It is entirely apparent, phenomenal, on the surface ; and therefore it cannot explain that which is half-hidden, which comes and goes, which passes from potentiality into actuality. But this is the characteristic of every real thing, every res completa. In so far as it exists, and is not merely possible, it has come into being ; it is its nature to pass from potentiality to actuality. We cannot have a better example of this than the human soul, in which we find continuous process along with unity and self-identity. Thus it seems to Leibniz that real things or substances are to be conceived as analogous to the human soul, as forms or living prin- ciples in a sense deeper than that of the later Scholastics, who had, indeed, almost entirely emptied the term ' form ' of signification. Going back to the source of these views that had so degenerated, Leibniz finds the nearest approach to what he is seeking in Aristotle's ' entelechy, ' the principle of a thing in the sense of its implicit perfect realization, what it is in the thing to be or become. Thus Leibniz supplements the Cartesian physics by the idea that mere body or matter is an abstraction, existing nowhere, and that every real existence has a soul or living principle. And in this way the Monadology restores to philosophy, with new force and meaning, the infinite number of forms which was the chief feature of the Peripatetic philosophy. Leibniz's relation to Atomist philosophy is for the most part a negative one, and it is hardly necessary to add anything to what has incidentally been said regarding it. He is on the side of modern science in rejecting the idea of an absolute vacuum. And when he sometimes speaks l6o INTRODUCTION of the Monads as atoms his object is probably to show that the Monadology expresses clearly what the atomists are groping for. His leading thought in this connexion is that a real whole presupposes a real unit, that is to say, a unit which is essentially connected with the whole, representative of it, and not in a merely accidental or indeterminate relation to it. The atomists are right, he would say, in insisting upon a real unit, but, on their view of reality, it is impossible to find any such unit \ Leibniz's ' Sufficient Reason ' in relation to the ' Cause ' of Descartes and Spinoza. When we look, not at what Leibniz was himself aware of doing but at what he actually did without clearly knowing it, we may regard his use of the principle of sufficient reason as a development of what was implied in the use which Descartes and Spinoza made of the notion of ' cause.' Descartes, as we have seen2, develops his system under the guidance of the principle of contradiction alone. But in order to pass from the subjectivity of the pure Ego to an objective, external reality, he finds it necessary to have recourse to the principle that everything must have an efficient cause which is at least as real as the effect (and may be more real than it). This principle he assumes without any attempt to demonstrate its validity, and it is the real basis of his proofs, in the first place, of the existence of God, and in the second place, of the existence of an external world 3. The proofs of the existence of God form the keystone of Descartes's system. Their function is to make up for the inevitable imper- fections of a logic based solely on the principle of contra- diction. Clinging, as he does, to the dualism of mind and 1 Cf. this Introduction, Part ii. pp. 27 sqq. 3 This Introduction, Part ii. pp. 58 sqq. 3 Cf. Meditation III and the mathematically arranged arguments in the Reponses aux Deuxiemes Objections. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 1 6 1 matter, of thought and external existence, Descartes could not rest satisfied with the idea of a most perfect being. He must get beyond the idea to the reality ; he must justify not one or another idea but thought itself. In the charac- teristics of * clearness ' and * distinctness ' in ideas he had found a criterion for the consistency of thought with itself. A clear and distinct idea completely satisfied thought, but it still remained to be shown that such an idea has objective validity ; that there actually exists that which it represents. Now according to Descartes, it is the truth- fulness, the consistency, the goodness of an actually existing God (who would not be perfect had He not these qualities) that assure to us the validity of our clear and distinct ideas. ' Even the principle,' says Descartes, ' which I have already taken for a rule, namely, that all the things which we clearly and distinctly conceive are true, is certain only because God is or exists, and because He is a perfect Being, and because all that we possess is derived from Him. ... If we did not know that all which we possess of real and true proceeds from a perfect and infinite Being, however clear and distinct our ideas might be, we should have no ground on that account for the assurance that they possessed the perfection of being true '.' Accordingly, as regards real existence (apart from that of the pure Ego), everything in Descartes's system ultimately turns upon this unexplained principle of cause, by means of which he proves the existence of God, and which he again employs in establishing the reality of the world. God must exist, for otherwise no adequate cause can be assigned for the existence of the idea of God in us. And again, we must postulate the real existence of external 1 Method, Part iv. (Veitch's Tr., p. 80). Cf. Meditation IV: 'It is impossible that God should ever deceive me ; since in all fraud and deceit one meets with some kind of imperfection ; and although it may seem that to be able to deceive is a mark of clever- ness or of power, the wish to deceive always indicates, without a doubt, feebleness or malice ; and accordingly such a wish cannot exist in God.' Cf. Hegel, Geschichte der Phil. iii. p. 319. ! 1 62 INTRODUCTION things as the cause of certain ideas in us, unless we are to suppose that God deceives us l. Spinoza takes the one substance, God, as his starting- point of absolute certainty, and accordingly proofs of the existence of God have for him no meaning. Nevertheless, he does not altogether dispense with the notion of cause. Ostensibly he reduces the relation of cause and effect to a logical connexion, like that between a geometrical figure and its properties. But he makes use of the notion of cause to introduce variety into the perfect unity of sub- stance by describing it as cause of itself (causa sui). And in his distinction between natura naturans and natura naturata he endeavours, by a further application of the notion of cause, to bridge the gulf which his logic has set between the infinite (as purely indeterminate) and finite or determinate existence. Natura naturans is substance expressed in attributes or ' God as the free cause of all that is.' Natura naturata is ' all that follows from the necessity of the Divine nature or from any one of the attributes of God, i. e. all modes of God's attributes, considered as things which exist in God, and without God can neither exist nor be conceived V In short, causa sui or substance is analyzed into two moments, cause (natura naturans) and effect (natura naturata) ; but both of these are ultimately the same thing. Apart from this distinction without a difference it would be impossible for Spinoza to identify his infinite substance with the actual world. And yet, in spite of it, for Spinoza the finite, as finite, remains unreal. Now this notion of cause, which Descartes and Spinoza employ without attempting to explain or justify it, is, in a more general form, acknowledged by Leibniz as an independent logical principle, that of sufficient reason. There must be, not merely an adequate cause but a sufficient reason for the existence of each individual thing. 1 Cf. Meditation VI, passim. 9 Ethics, Part i. prop. 29, Scholium. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 163 And as we have seen *, the sufficiency of the reason rests ultimately on the nature of God as perfect in wisdom, goodness, and power. Manifestly there is here a working- out of what is more vaguely implied in Descartes's repeated references to the perfection of the character of God as our warrant for the reality of things. And the argument of Spinoza (however inconsistent it may be) is based on the conviction that every finite thing must find its place in the one all-embracing system, that is to say, must follow from the nature of God in whom are all perfections. Thus the addition of the principle of suffi- cient reason to that of contradiction is not an entirely novel suggestion on the part of Leibniz, but is an out- growth of what was already involved in the reasonings of his immediate predecessors. It is a step towards the reconciling of their inconsistencies by bringing into clear consciousness a principle which they blindly and imper- fectly employed. The Philosophy of Wolff. The philosophy of Leibniz suffered grievously at the hands of his immediate disciples 2. Probably this was inevitable. Few of his writings were published in his lifetime, and his philosophical opinions were dispersed through masses of manuscript which might well be the despair of his friends. And the philosophical system J This Introduction, Part ii. p. 66. 2 'It has been with Leibniz as with several philosophers of antiquity, who might have said : "May God preserve us from our friends ; as for our enemies, we ourselves shall be able to protect ourselves from them." ' Kant, Entdeckung nach der alle neue Kritik der reinen Vernunft durch eine altere entbehrlich gemacht werden soil. Rosenkranz, i. 478 ; Hartenstein, iii. 390. Cf. Wallace, Logic of Hegel (snd ed.) ; Prolegomena, ch. 17. Kant himself in one of his earlier writings (Traume ernes Geistersehers, &c. ; Rosenkranz, vii. 45 ; Hartenstein, iii. 58) speaks of 'Leibniz's amusing idea, according to which we might perhaps swallow in our coffee atoms destined to become human souls.' And a naturalist of the end of last century, Otto F. Muller, thought that he had discovered Monads under the microscope ! M 2 164 INTRODUCTION itself must have seemed as broken as was the expression of it. The two principles of contradiction and sufficient reason stood side by side, and there was no clear account of the relation between them. A system with two independent principles can have no stability, and this defect must somehow be removed. On the other hand, Newton had triumphed in the long controversy, and his fame had led to Leibniz's discredit. Leibniz's metaphysics seemed in some points incompatible with the Newtonian physics, and must therefore to some extent be modified. This systematizing and modifying of the philosophy of Leibniz were accomplished by Christian Wolff (1679- X754)? wno himself, however, strongly objected to being called a mere disciple .of Leibniz, or an elaborator of the Leibnitian philosophy. Wolffs position may be regarded as in some respects a return to the Cartesian attitude of mind. His solution of the difficulty arising from the supposition of two co- ordinate first principles is to make the principle of sufficient reason a logical inference from that of contradiction, and thus to make the law of contradiction the one supreme law of thought. He holds that the difference between 'something' and 'nothing' is absolute, ' something' being that of which there is some notion, while ' nothing ' is that of which there is no notion 1. Thus everything must have a sufficient reason, i. e. some reason why it exists rather than does not «xist, for otherwise something would proceed out of nothing. But ex nihilo nihil fit : there is no middle term between ' something ' and * nothing V So in Wolff the antithesis of being and not-being is supreme, to the exclusion of the notion of becoming. ' The impos- sible is nothing.' And on the other hand, 'the possible is always something V It ought logically to follow that everything possible is actual, and that there is no distinc- tion between essence and existence. But at this point the 1 Oniologia, 57, 59. 2 Ibid. 70. 8 Ibid. 101, 102. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 165 Leibnitian influence reasserts itself, and Wolff becomes confused. His ruthless logic gives way. * Besides the possibility of a being, something else is still needed for its existence.' * Existence or reality is the complement of possibility1.' As an illustration of what he means he takes the case of a tree which is potentially in the seed, but which requires for its actual development (its exis- tence as a tree) the co-operation or complement of other existing things. Thus Wolff returns to the Leibnitian distinction between the ' possible' and the 'compossible,' after he has emptied of all meaning the principle of sufficient reason, on which the distinction rests. To put it otherwise, . if the actual existing ' something ' is more than a merely possible ' something ' (as Wolff's position here implies), then there must be a middle term between the actual 'something' and 'nothing.' And this, of course, is flatly contradictory of Wolff's original principle. Thus while Wolff makes a show of logical completeness and system, he is really hacking in pieces the philosophy of Leibniz. He is fascinated by its individualist element, the self-sufficiency and mutual exclusiveness of the Monads, which we have seen to be connected, in the thinking of Leibniz, with the survival of a narrow interpretation of the principle of contradiction2. Wolff carries to an ex- treme this tendency (which, after all, is not the supreme power in Leibniz's thought), and gives us, as the outcome of the bare principle of contradiction, an abstract indi- vidualism, just as Spinoza had already from the same principle developed an abstract universalism or pantheism. It is because of the essentially dogmatic character of the principle that such extremes can each be represented as flowing from it. As employed by Spinoza and by Wolff the principle can legitimately yield nothing but the bare self-identity of the data or assumptions with which each begins his work. Accordingly (as in this case) if the 1 Ontologia, 173, 174. 2 This Introduction, Part ii. p. 68. 1 66 INTRODUCTION presuppositions are in complete opposition to one another, we may have two contrary philosophical systems, both apparently flowing from the same first principle. Wolff, then, rejects the law of continuity and returns to a position which has some analogy with that of Descartes. Ostensibly his philosophy is a Monad ology ; really it is a kind of combination of Monadology with Atomism \ The Cartesian dualism is restored in the form of a distinction between spiritual and physical Monads. The spiritual Monads alone, in Wolff's opinion, deserve the name of Monads. The others are ' elements of things,' atomi naturae. These physical atoms or unconscious Monads are no longer regarded as living mirrors, repre- senting or perceiving the whole universe. They are still automata, but they are no longer souls. They have nothing in common with the spiritual Monads except the characteristics of unity, simplicity, and activity. Thus the whole of Leibniz's hypotheses regarding unconscious thinking, petites perceptions, &c., are thrown aside, and we have, in place of Descartes's two substances (thought and extension \ two sets of independent particular substances, the phenomena of the one set being thoughts and of the other set motions. As an inevitable consequence of this, the system of pre-established harmony, as Leibniz con- ceived it, disappears also. Wolff retains the name, but he regards the harmony not as a hypothesis by which to explain the relations of each independent particular sub- stance to eveiy other, but merely as an explanation of the connexion between soul and body, between spiritual atoms or Monads and corporeal atoms. According to Leibniz there could be no real interaction between Monads. But Wolff's * atoms of nature,' being1 purely physical, do really influence one another. He sees no difficulty in 1 Cf. Schelling, SammtUche Werkffj vol. vi. p. 116 : 'As often happens, the immediate successorsfof Leibniz set aside the really speculative part of his doctrine, rthe Monadology. For example the most celebrated of them, Wolff, admits it into his system only in the guise of a hypothesis.' ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 167 holding that motion can be transferred from one to another \ His difficulty is the original Cartesian problem — How can a purely thinking substance influence an abso- lutely non-thinking substance, or how can motion pass into thought ? And the pre-established harmony is, in Wolff's view, preferable to Occasionalism merely because it means one large and comprehensive initial miracle rather than an endless series of miraculous interventions of God. The natural, physical world is thus, according to Wolff, entirely subject to mechanical laws. There is, indeed, a realm of final causes, but the ends of things are com- pletely external to the things themselves. The final cause of a physical substance is not, as in the view of Leibniz, to be found in the nature of the substance itself, in its tendency towards self-realization, but in a law imposed upon it from outside. Thus the Wolffian teleology becomes almost childish, and suggests at times the naive explanations of things which are to be found in such writers as Bernardin de St. Pierre, who tells us that the melon is made large in comparison with other fruits to indicate that it ought to be eaten not in solitude but en famille, and that the cow with only one calf has four teats because the human race is fond of milk. Wolff hardly rises to this height, but he regards the stars as existing to give us light at night, and he points out that ' the light of day is of great advantage to us ; it enables us to carry on comfortably certain works which comparative darkness would make impossible or difficult, and also more expen- 1 Here again Wolff's position is glaringly ineon'sistent. His physical atoms or Monads are supposed to have a unity like that of the Leibnitian Monads. Yet he denies to them that which, for Leibniz, is the principle of this unity, viz. a soul differing not in kind but in degree from the conscious and rational soul. The atomi naturae are, in short, neither atoms nor Monads, but a contradictory jumble of the characteristics of both. Wolff regards the atomi naturae as 'in themselves indivisible,' and thus distinguishes them from atomi materiales, which are l in themselves divisible,' but which cannot be actually divided by any natural power. See Cosmologia, §§ 182 sqq., 186 sqq. and 232. l68 INTRODUCTION sive V This doctrine of final causes is a most essential part of the Wolffian system. For, according to Wolff, although nature is ultimately explicable by purely mechanical laws, we cannot actually reduce it to its ultimate elements, and consequently, in explaining physical phenomena as they are presented to us, we must continually have recourse to final causes. So also, while Wolff, adopting the phrase of Leibniz, speaks of God as freely choosing to create ' the best of all possible worlds,' he takes * best ' as meaning not • best on the whole,' but rather 'best for mankind.' Thus the optimism of Wolff is as shallow and arbitrary as his teleology, and it is not surprising that Kant, even in the early years when he followed Wolff on most points, deserted him in this matter, and turned back to views more akin to the greater thoughts of Leibniz. Relation of the Philosophy of Leibniz to that of Kant. In the earliest writings of Kant (who, through his teacher Knutzen, was bred a Wolffian), questions regard- ing space are discussed — questions, for instance, as to the reason why our space has three dimensions and as to the possibility and reality of other spaces having more than three dimensions. Kant was evidently already some- what dissatisfied with the current Wolman view of space and was beginning the course of inquiry that ultimately led to the doctrine of the Transcendental Aesthetic, a doc- trine more in harmony with the view of Leibniz than with that of Wolff2. According to Wolff, 'real' space must be distinguished from ' imaginary ' space, although 1 Verniinftige Gedanken von den Absichten der naturlichen Dinge. Cf. Ausfuhrliche Nachricht von seinen eigenen Schriften, §§ 186 sqq. 2 ' Leibniz's doctrine of sense as confused thought — confused in such a way as to make us represent the world as an order of things in space and time — though Kant explicitly rejects it, is in fact rather elaborated than superseded by his doctrine of space and time as forms of sensibility, under which alone experience is possible, but which prevent what is true of phenomena from being true of things in themselves, and knowledge from reaching the totality which it seeks.' T. H. Green, Works, vol. iii. p. 135. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 169 the results obtained from consideration of the notion of * imaginary ' space may justifiably be applied to ' real ' space '. 'Real' space is the order of co-existing things2 and is inseparable from the things themselves. God alone can have a perfectly adequate notion of it and can thus actually perceive its continuity. But we can form an abstract or ' imaginary ' notion of space, by thinking it as distinct from (or indifferent to) the co-existing things of which it is an * order ' ; and this imaginary space is, of course, homogeneous and continuous. The space of mathematics and physics is thus t imaginary space ' ; but it is such that the laws of mathematics and physics are valid in relation to 'real' space. Manifestly we have here neither the view of Leibniz nor that of Newton, but a doctrine which points to a possible reconciliation between them. On the one hand, space is not merely confused perception. As space it has reality : it is a real order in which physical things exist. But, on the other hand, this real space is not the space of the mathematician. He deals with a kind of projection or symbol of it, and thus the Newtonian position also is without WoliF s assent. It might easily be shown that the Wolffian doctrine of space is riddled with inconsistencies, of a kind similar to those which have been noticed in Wolff's account of individual substances. But the matter of main interest is that Kant received the problem of space in the form which Wolff had given it 3, and that through- 1 Ontologia, 599. 2 In analogy with time which is 'the order of successive things in a continuous series/ space is defined as 'the order of simul- taneous things, in so far as they co-exist.' Ontologia, 589. Cf. Qosmologia, 56. 3 Kant's criticism of Leibniz illustrates this. Cf. Fortschritte der Metaphysik seit Leibniz und Wolff' (Bosenkranz, i. 516; Hartenstein, iii. 441) : ' The principle of the identity of indiscernibles (princi- pium identitatis indiscemibilium) is that, if from A and B, which, in respect of all their internal characteristics (of quality and of quantity) are entirely alike, we make a concept as of two different things, we are in error, and we ought to have taken them for one and the same thing (numero eadem). Leibniz could not admit that J 70 INTRODUCTION out the writings of his pre-critical period, we find Kant working towards a view of space in which the Leibnitian and Newtonian positions shall be reconciled. Although he does not himself express it in this way, his problem might fairly be regarded as that of finding a single Con- ception of space which can take the place both of the * real ' and of the * imaginary ' space of Wolff. In what sense can space be regarded as at once real and ideal ? Not in the Wolffian sense ; for that practically involves a circulus in definiendo : i simultaneous or co-existing ' physical things presuppose space. Nor is the Newtonian view more satisfactory-, for, while it recognizes that space is prior to actual cases of spatial existence and while it maintains the reality of space, it implies that the whole universe is set in space and that the spatial system of relations has a real existence independent of the things related. Accordingly, through a course of thinking which we need not here trace \ Kant arrives at the position which he expounds in the Critique of Pure Reason, namely, that space is a form presupposed in the possibility of our sense-experience. It is not in any way given ab extra ; but it is the condition of there being externality for us. It is not a thing in itself, a real object ; but as it is a per- fectly pure perception, free from all the contingent detail we could still distinguish them through their places in space (as it is possible to perceive quite similar and equal spaces outside of one another without being able to say that they are one and the same space, for otherwise we could put the whole of infinite space into a cubic inch or less). Leibniz could not admit this, for he re- cognizes no other distinction among things than that which is made through notions [Begriffe], and refuses to allow any way of repre- sentation specifically distinct from this, such as intuition [An- schauung], and more especially intuition a priori. On the contrary he thought that this must be reduced to pure notions [Begriffe] of co-existence or succession, and thus he set himself against common sense, which will never be persuaded that the existence of a drop of water in one place makes it impossible for a perfectly similar and equal drop to exist in another place.' 1 For a full account see Caird's Critical Philosophy of Kant, vol. i. Introduction, ch. 5, especially pp. 164-168 and 178-182. Also bk. i. ch. 2, pp. 304, 305. Cf. Hutchison Stirling, Text-Book to Kant, PP- 34-43 and 366 sqq. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 171 of sense, it satisfies the requirements of Newtonian mathematics even better than if it were an independent entity. On the other hand, while it belongs to perception or direct intuition and is therefore not, as Leibniz and WoMf held, a relation or order among things which are prior to it, yet it is subjective or ideal, it belongs to our minds, and accordingly the difficulties inseparable from the Newtonian view of space (as expounded by Clarke, for instance) are avoided. .But mere sense-perception under the forms of space and time is not, according to Kant, a complete experience. It requires the complement of conception, which is the function of the understanding. Here Kant believed him- self to be in complete opposition to Leibniz, and yet it may well be doubted whether the opposition is really so great as Kant supposed it to be. In the Critique of Pure Reason Kant does draw a much sharper line between per- ception and conception than Leibniz did. Kant may be said to regard the difference as one of kind, while for Leibniz it is a difference of degree. Leibniz, as we have seen, gave to perception an exceedingly wide meaning, a meaning which includes conception and representation of every kind, whether conscious or unconscious. But Kant's l perception ' is limited to sense-representation. Nevertheless Kant's t perception ' is avowedly abstract, and the confused perception, which is Leibniz's name for sense-knowledge, is abstract also, though in a somewhat different way. In fact, for Kant the distinction between perception and conception is a distinction between abstract elements in a concrete whole of experience, while the corresponding distinction in Leibniz is a distinction be- tween degrees of perfection in one quality or function. Thus for Kant sense-perception is abstract, because its reality always implies a complementary element, while for Leibniz it is abstract because it is imperfectly deve- loped, because it contains the potentiality of greater perfection. The weakness of the Kantian position is its 172 INTRODUCTION tendency to over-sharpen the distinction between percep- tion and conception by ignoring the idea of development, while the defect of Leibniz is his inclination to define the common quality or function ('perception') by its lowest rather than its highest terms, to interpret it, not as essen- tially self-consciousness, which is its most perfect develop- ment, but as mere representation or multiplicity in unity, to which consciousness and self-consciousness are added characteristics ]. Yet while Kant makes an advance from the position of Leibniz, they are on similar lines, and we can read their reconciliation in Hegel 2. Leibniz does not give any clear account of the relations between the principle of contradiction and that of suffi- cient reason, as he uses them in his philosophy ; but it is evident that he considered them to be, in some way, ultimately in harmony. The tendency of Kant, on the other hand, is to emphasize the distinction between them, while treating each, apart from the other, as abstract. The course of Kant's pre-critical thinking makes this clear. He begins with the Wolffian view that the principle of sufficient reason is reducible to that of contradiction 3, and accordingly, that the principle of contradiction is the sole ultimate principle of knowledge. But gradually he comes to see that the principle of contradiction has to do with nothing but the form of thought and that it yields merely a self-consistent system of knowledge, based on dogmatic 1 In this, I think, there is to be found the explanation of the separation (almost amounting to a distinction of kind) between rational souls and the other Monads, which Leibniz makes with such apparent inconsistency. Cf. this Introduction, Part iii.p. 116. 2 ' The doctrines of Leibniz formed the permanent atmosphere of Kant's mind. His reading of Hume in middle life no doubt helped to determine the mode in which he absorbed and trans- formed them ; but it was upon them, as we find in the Critique no less than in his earlier writings, that his mind constantly worked, and there would be a better case, at any rate, for describing him as a corrected and developed Leibniz than for putting him in such a relation to any one else/ T. H. Green, Works, vol. iii. p. 134. 3 Cf. Principiorum primorum cognitionis metaphysicae nova dilucidatio (T755) (Rosenkranz, i. 4; Hartenstein, iii. 4). ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 173 presuppositions. It ensures order and necessary con- nexion in thought, but it is inadequate to reality. It gives the logical ground of things (logisclie G-rund) but not the ground of their reality (Eeal-grund) \ Thus the principle of contradiction is insufficient when treated as the ultimate principle of metaphysics. Kant develops this position in connexion with the problem of proving the existence of God. He rejects, as a begging of the question, the Cartesian demonstration which maintains that existence is necessarily involved in the perfection of the most perfect Being. Existence, Kant says, cannot be a predicate. That is to say, you cannot take out of any subject more than is contained in it ; the principle of contradiction will never entitle you to pass from any mere idea to the reality of that idea. Pure thought, determined by the principle of contradiction, always presupposes something 'given,' and thus reality must ultimately lie outside of pure thought. Thus, for example, the real cause of anything is always more than a mere reason : a causal connexion is not a merely logical con- nexion. It is this line of thinking that leads Kant to emphasize the distinction between logical understanding and empirical sense, and to lay stress on l experience ' (un- rationalized and unexplained) as the ground of reality, in a way that recalls the position of Locke. Thus, while admitting the certainty of mathematics, Kant protests against the use of a purely mathematical method in deal- ing with metaphysics or with the theory of knowledge, on the ground that such a method is ' merely synthetic, ' that is to say, on the ground that it does not analyze actual experience but deduces from (or builds upon) arbi- 1 Cf. Der einzig mogliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins Gottes (1763) (Rosenkranz, i. 161 ; Hartenstein, vi. n). Kant makes advances towards this position in the Essay on Die falsche Spitsfindigkeit der vier syllogistischen Figuren (1762) (Rosenkranz, i. 55 ; Hartenstein, i. i), and in the Versuch den Begriff der negatiren Grossen in die Weltweisheit einzufuhren (1763) (Rosenkranz, i. 113; Harten- stein, i. 19). 174 INTRODUCTION trary or at least mind-made presuppositions \ Finally in the Critique of Pure Reason we have Kant's solution of the problem as to the relations between a priori and a posteriori, thought and experience. And his contention is that the a priori is not merely that which is self-evident and can be expressed in an analytic judgment, but that which experience universally and necessarily involves as the condition of its possibility. This, after all, is but the working out of what is out- lined by Leibniz, when he insists on l compossibility, ' or necessity arising from the system of things, as the ground of reality. For Leibniz the real is the 'fitting,' that which has its place in the best possible system or world : for Kant the real is that which is in an orderly experience constituted by principles which are the logical a priori conditions of its possibility. In the philosophy of Kant, accordingly, we have a more thorough application of the principle of sufficient reason, which Leibniz had imper- fectly applied. Leibniz's explanation of the existence of the actual system of things as the result of a choice among all possible worlds is due to the inconsistency in his posi- tion which comes from working with two co-ordinate first principles. The totality of possible worlds is at once a system and not a system. If it were a system, the choice by God of the best possible world would be determined by the nature of the whole system of possibles. The best possible world would be the best world in that system, and thus the problem of Leibniz would not be solved by the * choice/ but would merely be carried a stage farther back. On the other hand, if the totality of possible worlds were not a system, the choice of God would prac- tically be arbitrary : at least it would be grounded on no 1 Of. Untersuchung uber die Deutlichkeit der Grundsdtze der naturlichen Thcologie und der Moral (1764^ (Rosenkranz, i. 75 ; Hartenstein, i. 63). See also Kant's Inaugural Thesis on becoming Professor in Konigs- berg, De mundi sensililis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis (1770), in which the distinction between sense and understanding is brought to the sharpest point. (Rosenkranz, i. 301 ; Hartenstein, iii. 123.) ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 175 reason intelligible to us. God would choose the best possible world ; but it would be the best possible for no other reason than that He chose it. Thus the totality of possible ideal worlds has the appearance of being a system, while really it is not. It is this ambiguity that conceals the fundamental inconsistency of Leibniz — the incon- sistency of regarding God as both within the system of things and quite outside of it (as the Creator), making Him at once the source of the whole system of mutually exclusive Monads and the highest Monad of the series, without whom the system would itself be incomplete. The principle of sufficient reason, rightly understood, in- volves the supposition of one all-embracing system ; but •though Leibniz had certainly an inkling of the truth of this, his individualistic tendency and his dread of Spinozism prevented him from fully realizing it. For Kant there is but one system of experience, that which actually exists. The supposition of a choice among possible worlds is no part of his philosophy. But in Kant's doctrine the t thing-in-itself ' performs very much the same function as did the ' choice ' in Leibniz's scheme of things. Each is a way of allowing for a possible reality other than the actual system, although the need of this arises from one cause in Leibniz, and from another in Kant. Leibniz wishes to avoid a doctrine of blind neces- sity : Kant is afraid of a pure relativity. They both feel that the ultimate ground of the system of mutually related things must be sought in some principle outside the system itself l. The dogmatism of Leibniz appears in his 1 Cf. Critique of Pure Reason, Eosenkranz, ii. 524 ; Hartensteiii, ii. 513 (Meiklejohn's Tr., p. 414) : 'The notions of reality, of sub- stance, of causality, of necessary existence itself, have no signifi- cance in determining any object, beyond their use in making possible the empirical cognition of a thing. They may thus be used to explain the possibility of things in the world of sense, but they cannot be used to explain the possibility of the unicerse itself; since in this case the ground of explanation must lie outside the world, and can therefore be no object of a possible experience. Now, relatively to the world of sense, I may admit such an incom- prehensible being, the object of a mere idea ; though I may not 176 INTRODUCTION making this principle a real and independent 'constitutive ' ground of the world, and he glosses over the difficulty of explaining its relation to the world by metaphors such as the ' Divine choice ' and the producing of created Monads by continual * fulgurations of Divinity/ The criticism of Kant, on the other hand, leads him to interpret this ultimate principle negatively, as a merely 'regulative' idea, of the absolute nature of which the speculative reason can say nothing. Its reality, however, is assured to us by the practical reason, and in it we must suppose that there is a reconciliation of necessity and freedom, of the kingdom of nature and the kingdom of grace, of mechanism and teleology. We cannot give a completely satisfactory account of the phenomenal world as a system governed by final causes, for we have no speculative knowledge of the ultimate intelligence and the ends it sets before itself. We may guess at final causes ; but we cannot understand their producing anything, apart from mechanical causes. And on the other hand, while we cannot help regarding the phenomenal world as a mechanical system, * absolutely no human reason (in fact no finite reason like ours in quality, however much it may surpass it in degree) can hope to understand the production of even a blade of grass by mere mechanical causes1.' We must, in certain cases, postulate adaptation to ends. But we can quite conceive an intelligence which can think the world, not discursively from part to part as we do, but immediately and completely, from whole to part, and for such an intelligence, final and efficient cause, freedom and necessity, would be harmonized. For it to know and to create the world would be the admit its existence in itself. ... It is only a something in general which I know not in itself, but to which, as a ground of systematic unity in cognition, I attribute characteristics analogous to the notions of the understanding in the empirical sphere.' 1 Kant, Critique of Judgment, Part ii. div. ii. § 77 (Rosenkranz, iv. 301 ; Hartenstein, vii. 288 ; Bernard's Tr., p. 326). See the whole passage. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 177 same thing : creation would be its thought. Thus Leib- niz and Kant are at one in placing the ultimate synthesis of things, the sufficient reason of experience, in some- thing that is beyond experience itself, and that is related to experience in a way which stands in need of further explanation. Leibniz, however, falls into a contradiction which Kant avoids. For Leibniz regards God as at once the highest of the Monads (the ultimate term in the series) and the Creator of the Monads, i. e. the sufficient reason of the world which they constitute. But if God is one of the series of Monads, it seems impossible to regard Him as their sufficient reason, as choosing to create the system of which He is an element. And on the other hand, if the essence of the Monads is to repre- sent the universe, and if He factuspurus) perfectly realizes the universe within Himself, having perfectly clear and distinct perception, what place is there for a system of Monads apart from Him ? Kant avoids the difficulty by the sharp distinction he draws between experience and the thing-in-itself. He can thus regard God as related to the world in a way which we may attempt to describe as causal, creative, or otherwise, but which it is impossible for us ever with certainty to define \ In short, so far as our theoretical knowledge of things is concerned, the account we give of the relation of God to the world is simply a useful hypottiesis, by means of which we may give unity to our knowledge, and avoid the fallacies of 1 Cf. Critique of Pure Eeason (Hartenstein, ii. 508 sqq. ; Rosenkranz, ii. 519 sqq.), Meiklejohn, pp. 410 sqq.: 'The notion of a supreme intelligence is a mere idea, that is to say, its objective reality does not consist in its being immediately referable to an object (for in this sense we cannot establish its objective validity) but it is merely a schema of the notion of a thing in general, a schema constructed according to the conditions of the greatest unity of reason, and serving only to produce the greatest systematic unity in the empirical use of our reason, inasmuch as we deduce this or that object of experience from the imagined object of this idea as the ground or cause of the object of experience.' Cf. also Rosen- kranz, ii. 598 ; Hartenstein, ii. 581 ; Meiklejohn, p. 471. N 178 INTRODUCTION dogmatism1. Yet, while Kant thus escapes the contra- diction in Leibniz's view, he cannot be said to give us a satisfactory solution of the difficulty2. The Influence of Leibniz on Fichte. In the modern idealism which first took shape in the writings of Fichte, there may be traced the influence of certain leading ideas in the philosophy of Leibniz, to which Kant had inevitably done less than justice. The work of Fichte is generally regarded as an endeavour to give systematic unity to the philosophy of Kant by get- ting rid of the thing-in-itself, regarded as entirely outside of experience. Indeed, until Kant repudiated his inter- pretation, Fichte regarded himself as an expositor of the true Kantian view, and a defender of the critical philo- sophy against the misunderstandings of its unintelligent disciples, Fichte's main idea is that experience (in the Kantian sense) has its basis in a self-consciousness (an Ich-heit) which is itself the root of the distinction between the empirical ego and the empirical non-ego, between subject and object. Both subject and object are logically involved in the original self-consciousness, out of which all experience, both in its matter and in its form, may be deduced. Thus all reference to a reality beyond experience becomes unmeaning as well as unnecessary. The unity of the universe is maintained with pantheistic 1 D. Nolen (La Critique de Kant et la Metaphysique de Leibniz, pp. 331 et sqq.) regards the Monadology as a necessary complement to the ' Criticism ' of Kant. It seems to him that the * thing-in-itself has, in the philosophy of Kant, a function similar to that of the 1 possible thing ' or ' essence ' in the system of Leibniz. An ingenious attempt has also been make by Otto Riedel (Die Monado- logischen Bestimmungen in Kants Lehre vom Ding an sicti) to show that the things-in-themselves, in so far as they are conceived as positive, have the characteristics of Monads. There is a hint of the same view in Ueberweg's Commentary on the two editions of the Critique of Pure Reason. 2 For Kant's account of his own relation to Leibniz see Appendix E, p. 208. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 179 completeness ; and the system of Fichte has well been described as t Spinoza in terms of Kant V Now the need of a thing-in-itself, such as Kant postu- lates, arises from the thoroughness of his separation between perception and conception, between sense and understanding. They are correlative ; yet they are treated by him as if quite independent, so that the result of their combination is a merely phenomenal world. Per- ception cannot evolve from itself the forms of the under- standing, through which alone it loses its blindness ; and conception cannot produce for itself the matter of sense and experience, without which it is empty. But this dualism indicates, in a negative way, the necessity of a noumenal world, however completely such a world may be beyond the reach of our intellectual comprehension or proof. It is in revulsion from dogmatism that Kant holds this position. And thus he is continually pointing out that the great error of Leibniz is that of regarding experience as a system of concepts, which may constitute an internally self-consistent whole, but which has no cer- tain contact with reality. Such a dogmatism, Kant holds, has no answer to scepticism, and thus to give up the sharp distinction between perception and conception is to lose our grasp of reality and truth. Accordingly it is not surprising to find that, in setting aside the thing-in-itself (as Kant understood it), Fichte goes back to the doctrine of Leibniz and proceeds to develop, under new conditions, some of its leading ideas2. 1 Adamson's Fichte (Blackwood's Philosophical Classics), p. 130. 2 ' The time is come for reviving the philosophy of Leibniz. . . . Nothing is further removed from the thought of Leibniz than the speculative dream of a world, of things-in-themselves, which no mind comprehends or knows, but which nevertheless acts upon us and produces all our ideas. The first of his thoughts, that which he makes his starting-point, is, that the representations of external things arise in the soul in virtue of its own laws, as in an isolated world, and as if nothing were present in it except God (the Infinite) and the soul (consciousness of the Infinite). ... In thus expressing himself Leibniz spoke for philosophers. But now-a-days people will insist on philosophizing, even when philosophy is the last K 2 l8o INTRODUCTION Leibniz, in antagonism to the dualist position of Descartes, does not lay stress on the distinction of subject and object, but conceives the universe as an infinity of subjects, each self-sufficient and 'in the sea of life enisled.' For Kant, the distinction of subject and object is all in all. Fichte still gives full weight to the distinction, but conceives it as overcome in the unity of self-consciousness, or rather as flowing necessarily from that unity in its most abstract and indefinite form, and being lost in that unity in its highest and most perfect form. Thus, according to Leibniz, the whole succession of a Monad's states,' all its perceptions of the universe, proceed spontaneously from within itself, t as if there were only God and itself in the world l ' ; and every created Monad contains within itself both matter and form, which are in reality degrees of one power or function. Similarly, the ego of Fichte, the primal self-consciousness, is a perfectly spontaneous force, producing from within itself the empirical ego and non- ego, subject and object, making its own external world, projecting that world through the power of imagination, and continually striving towards the ultimate overcoming of this distinction between outer and inner in a pure * intellectual intuition.' Accordingly Fichte throws down the barriers which Kant had raised between perception and conception, and returns to the position of Leibniz that all knowledge is one great process of development, though, of course, he gives a very different account of this development from that which we find in Leibniz2. thing they are fitted for. If anyone tells us that no idea [Vor- stellung] can arise in us from an external action, there is endless astonishment. To be a philosopher one must believe that the Monads have windows, through which things come and go.' (Schelling, Sammtliche Werke, vol. i. do. Ideen zu einer Philosophic der Natur, commended by Fichte, Werke, i. 515 note.) 1 Lettre a Foucher (1686), (G. i. 382). Cf. New System. § 14. 3 ' The final notion of Fichte' s philosophy, expressed more clearly in the later works than in the Wissenschaftslehre, is that of the divine or spiritual order of which finite spirits are the manifestation or realization, and in the light of which human life and its surroundings appear as the continuous progress in ever higher stages towards realization of the final end of reason. Under this ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY l8l The reality of the world of sense is for Fichte a result of the activity of imagination. Our mind creates our sensa- tions ; but it creates them unconsciously, and thus our imagination attributes them to things outside of us, objectifies them. Yet imagination does not give us mere illusions, but truths more or less perfectly expressed. * If it be shown, as the present system should show, that upon this activity of imagination rests the possibility of our consciousness, our life, our being for ourselves, that is to say, our being as ego [unseres Seyn als Jcfc], this activity of imagination cannot cease, unless we are to make abstraction from our ego, which would involve a contradiction, since that which makes abstraction cannot make abstraction from itself. This activity of imagina- tion, then, does not deceive us, but gives us truth, the only possible truth \ ' There are, as it were, two sides to our knowledge of things. In so far as it is sensation (that is to say, an idea unconsciously created by the mind) it is a product of the non-ego, the object ; while in so far as it is an idea consciously ' projected ' by us or referred to something, it is a product of the ego, the subject. But the action of ego and non-ego is reciprocal, and they both have their source in the original self-consciousness from which they necessarily proceed2. It is, of course, beyond the scope of our intention to consider the many essential differences between the systems of Leibniz and of Fichte : to have indicated their connexion is sufficient. And the words of Schelling may conception, the oppositions of thought which play so important a part in philosophy — being and thought, mind and nature, soul and body, freedom and law, natural inclination and moral effort, mechanism and teleology — are reconciled. They appear in their due place as different aspects of the several stages in and through which the spiritual order is realized.' Adamson, Fichte, pp. 219, 220. 1 Fichte, SammtUche Werke, i. 227. 3 'The ego, as understood in common unscientific language, posits neither the external object nor itself, but both are posited through general and absolute thinking, and through this the object is given for the ego, as well as the ego for itself.' Fichte, Werke, ii. 562. I 1 82 INTRODUCTION be taken as showing that this connexion was from the first fully realized. 'Since Leibniz/ he says, 'if we set aside secondary doctrines which do not count, we see that the real, the finite, is generally placed in the region of the ideal. The whole real world has no existence in itself, but only in the representations \_Vorstellungen] of the soul. . . . Fichte takes up this idealism which is a denial of the independent being of the real, and, in this regard, he does not go beyond Leibniz. The only difference between them is this. Leibniz cannot explain why the soul or the Monad is subject to affections which produce in it finite representations ; or, if he tries to find the cause of this, he is obliged to place it in God, in the Infinite, which involves him in inevitable contradictions. Fichte, on the other hand, finds that the finite nature of the soul has its explanation in the absolutely free activity of the soul itself and results from this, that the soul by its own act posits itself for itself as finite, as separated from the absolute all, and consequently imposes on itself the ne- cessity of contemplating no longer this absolute all, but only the negations, limitations, bounds of its infinity V Accordingly it may be said generally that in the philo- sophy of Leibniz will and intelligence (appetition and perception) are co-ordinate principles of things (the will of God, for instance, not being prior to His understand- ing nor His understanding to His will), while the philosophy of Fichte is essentially a practical idealism, in which will (in however undefined a form) is ultimate and predominant. The ' principle of the best ' (the ten- dency to realize the moral order which is the expression of the infinite good will) is with Leibniz the determining principle of actual, as distinct from merely possible existence, while with Fichte it is the ultimate ground of all reality, of the one system of things2. 1 Schelling, Propaedeutik zur neueren Philosophic. Werke, vol i. p. 125. 2 An excellent account of Fichte's historical position is given in ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 183 Schopenhauer. As regards the main principles of his philosophy, Schopenhauer (however unconsciously) follows Fichte1. His starting-point is the Kantian distinction between the intelligible or noumenal and the empirical or phenomenal character of a real subject2. As in the philosophy of Fichte, the ultimate reality is will. The l intelligible character' is a will, which is the source of the 'empirical character ' ; and in general will is a pure activity which is the source of the system of phenomena. Thus the world is will + idea (i. e. Vorstellung, representation, phe- nomenon). The absolute is the purely practical activity of will, which gives rise to the relative or mutually conditioned, in a way which is beyond explanation, for our understanding cannot pass the limits of the conditioned, the phenomenal world. But this ultimate will is essentially destitute of anything that can fairly be described as ethical character. The world is not a progress towards the realization of the best, but rather an unfortunate episode' in the existence of the eternal will, and the highest good is to be attained not by allow- ing this will or striving (will to live) to have free course in us, but by suppressing it as much as possible. The expression, 'the world as will and idea,' recalls the Leibnitian view of substance as essentially appetition 4- perception. But Schopenhauer, like Fichte, gives to will a metaphysical priority, which is not attributed Wallace's Logic of Hegel, Prolegomena (and ed.), ch. n. See also chs. 12 and 13 for an account of Schelling with suggestive references to Leibniz. In ch. 13 there is a lucid explanation of the various meanings of the term ' Evolution,' as it is used by Leibniz and by later writers. Cf. vol. ii. p. 424. 1 ' Except his pessimism, which is no necessary consequence of the system, there is absolutely nothing in Schopenhauer's philo- sophy which is not contained in the later works of Fichte.' Adamson, Fichte, p. 219. Though this is the statement of an expert, I venture to think it a little too sweeping. 2 Critique of Pure Reason, Rosenkranz, ii. 422 ; Hartenstein, ii. 420 ; Meiklejohn, p. 333. 184 INTRODUCTION to it by Leibniz. Again, Schopenhauer, reducing the cate- gories of Kant to causality ( interpreted in a wide sense), gives great importance to the principle of sufficient reason which (in one or other of four different forms) he regards as the governing principle of the phenomenal world. 'All our ideas \_VorsteUungen] stand to one another in a regular [gesetzmassig} connexion, which as to its form is determiiiable a priori, and on account of which nothing self-sufficient and independent, nothing separate and de- tached, can become an object for us. It is this connexion which the principle of sufficient reason, in its univer- sality, expresses1.' The principle of contradiction is ostensibly subordinated to that of sufficient reason, it being regarded as one of the general laws of thinking, discovered by induction and used as a judgment 'meta- logically true,' which may be the ground or sufficient reason of other judgments2. But here there is clearly an inconsistency between Schopenhauer's logical theory and his metaphysic. His absolute, the ultimate will, is (however far he may be from acknowledging it) really determined by the principle of contradiction, in its abstract form, for the will is conceived as that which absolutely is, that which is apart from all relation, that which may, in some mysterious way, produce a system of differences, but which has an identity that is perfectly independent of them. Accordingly, while Schopenhauer indicates the deeper and more comprehensive interpreta- tion of the principle of sufficient reason as underlying that of contradiction, he does not allow it to mould his system. Herbart. Another thinker who owes something to Leibniz and something more to Kant and to Fichte, is Herbart (1776- 1841). He is not content to subordinate the principle of 1 Ueber die vierfache Wurzel des Satees vom zureichenden Grunde, ch. 3, § 16.. 2 Cp. Ueber die vierfache Wurzel, &c., ch. 5, § 33. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 185 sufficient reason to that of contradiction, but he practically endeavours to do without the former principle as far as possible. The task of philosophy he regards as that of eliminating the contradictions that appear in common consciousness by transforming the ideas which are given in it *. This transformation, for Herbart, practically means abstraction. Every bit of experience, being given, has something real in it 2. But its reality is that which it is, apart from conditions or relations to other things. The real is always something, a quale, a ' this ' or ' that ' of some kind. But it is absolute position (in the Fichtean sense) or affirmation without negation ; it has absolute self-identity, so that it is perfectly simple and not, like the Monad of Leibniz, a substance involving in its unity a plurality of qualities ; and it is pure quality, without any quantitative element or aspect, so that it is neither a divisible totality nor an unbroken continuum. These * reals, ' like the Monads, are infinite in number, and each is different from every other. But they are absolutely unalterable, they have no characteristic analogous to the perception of Leibniz, and they are not impenetrable, for any number of them may equally be thought as occupying or as not occupying the same point in space. Like the Monads, no one ' real ' can act upon another ; otherwise they would cease to be absolute. And each ' real ' is the immediate cause of one and only one phenomenon of experience, so that the static variety of the world is due to the power of 'self-preservation' (SeWsterhaltung) in each ' real. ' The actual changes which we find in experience are due to the different aspects in which the ' reals ' appear, when they are in different relations to one another, although their true natures remain unchanged (as in the phenomena of colour contrasts). And these 'different 1 ' Mere uncritical experience or merely empirical knowledge only offers problems ; it suggests gaps, which indeed further re- flexion serves at first only to deepen into contradictions.' Wallace, Hegel's Philosophy of Mind, p. Ixiii. 2 * Wieviel Schein, soviel Hindeutung auf s Sein.' l86 INTRODUCTION relations of the ' reals ' to one another are, again, due to the possibility of conceiving the ' reals ' as both together in one point and apart from one another. Accordingly the soul, being a ' real/ must not be represented as having in itself powers, faculties, qualities, &c. It is absolutely simple, and has nothing but * self-preservation,' which apparently is little more than a permanent possibility of relation to other 'reals.' None of the functions and characteristics of mind belong to it intrinsically. They are to be ascribed to other things, quite as much as to the mind or soul itself. They are merely names for the phenomena or aspects of certain ; reals ' (one of which is the soul) in certain relations to one another. These phenomenal (of course, not real) interactions of the ' reals ' admit of mathematical calculation, and accordingly Herbart is the father of those who apply mathematical methods in empirical psychology1. This is natural in one whose thought is so completely dominated by the abstract use of the principle of contra- diction. And, in short, if we leave out of account the influence of Fichte upon his psychology, we may regard Herbart's work as a remodelling of that of Leibniz, on the supposition that the principle of sufficient reason is to be dropped. Hegel's Solution of the Dualism in Leibniz. In the philosophy of Hegel we have a solution of the dualism between the principle of contradiction and that of sufficient reason, as they are used and conceived by Leibniz. The problem indicated by this dualism under- lies the whole course of German speculation from the time of Leibniz onwards. Wolff, in a negative way, gave 1 His application of mathematical methods, however, differs entirely from that which occurs in the psycho-physics of the Fechner School, and in modern physiological psychology. For a full explanation, see Wallace, Hegel's Philosophy of Mind, pp. Ixviii sqq. It may also be noted that Leibniz's theories regarding un- conscious and petites perceptions are developed and applied in the psychology of Herbart. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ^ PHILOSOPHY 187 precision to the problem by suggesting the most superficial possible solution, reducing the principle of sufficient reason to that of contradiction. This (though Wolff perhaps did not realize it) was little better than telling Leibniz that he had discovered a mare's nest. Kant, on the other hand, gives positive precision to the problem by the sharpness of his distinction between the absolute and the relative, while Fichte and Schelling, in different ways, endeavour to make explicit the unity to which the Kantian divisions point. Their re-employment of the principle of development or progressive self-realization, which is so important a feature of Leibniz's thinking, brings us to the verge of Hegel's solution of the problem. Hegel practi- cally reverses the procedure of Wolff, by showing that the principle of contradiction presupposes that of sufficient reason, and that each by itself is an abstract expression of the principle of self-consciousness1. The real is not merely in se (as it would be if the abstract principle of contradiction were ultimate), nor is it merely in alio (as it would be if the abstract principle of sufficient reason were ultimate, which, of course, no one maintains). But the real is that which becomes itself through being in alio, through being not itself. There is no such thing as a purely analytic or a purely synthetic judgment ; but when we attribute any quality to a subject, we attribute to it not merely a difference from other things but a oneness with that from which we differentiate it 2. The universe is a system of such perfect unity that the oppo- sites it contains are all contraries and never contradictories. Absolute contradictories or absolute differences are ab- stractions. To say, as did Leibniz, that no two things are exactly the same implies that no two things (not even the most extreme opposites) are entirely different. A must 1 See Caird's Hegel (Blackwood's Philosophical Classics), chs. 7 and 8. Also Wallace, Prolegomena to the Logic of Hegel (and ed.), ch. 30. 2 Cf. Caird, Critical Philosophy of Kant, vol. ii. pp. 64 sqq. 1 88 INTRODUCTION have something in common with not-A, if their opposition is to have any meaning. l The other stands over against its other1.' That is to say, their difference must have some ground, some underlying unity. And on the other hand, every identity, even the identity of a thing with itself, implies some difference. There is no pure ground, no absolute first principle, independent of a sufficient reason. Hegel regards the universe as itself one absolute system. The world we know is the only world, and it is not a merely phenomenal system, the expression of something heterogeneous with it (like the arc electric light between two opposite points of carbon , nor is it an inexplicable product of something other than itself, such as an unconditioned will, nor yet is it the production of some noumenal absolute. It hangs upon nothing ; it needs nothing to hang upon. The universe is one system of endless mutual determinations, yet not a merely static system nor a system of cyclical revolutions, endlessly repeated, which would involve the supposition of an external absolute as the source or support of all. It is rather an evolution of that whose end is in its beginning, that whose development is free, because, being all-com- prehensive, it is perfectly self-determined. Thus Hegel points out that 'it is the notion which Leibniz had in his eye when he spoke of sufficient ground and urged the study of things under its point of view.' By the notion Hegel means ' a content objectively and intrin- sically determined and hence self-acting.' This would sufficiently describe the Monad of Leibniz if we keep out of view the Monad's absolute particularity, its isolation as one of an infinite series of independent units, or, in other words, if we omit from the conception of the Monad all that is due to the principle of contradiction, interpreted abstractly as a principle of pure or immediate self-identity. This isolation, of course, is an essential element in 1 Hegel, Logic, § 119 (Wallace's Tr., and ed., p. 222). See the whole passage, and also pp. 224 sqq. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY 189 Loibniz's conception of the Monad, and the result is that while his speculation points to a view of the universe as one system in which the elements are intrinsically and not externally combined, he does not go far enough to secure this metaphysical position, just as he does not push his logical analysis far enough to reconcile the principles of contradiction and sufficient reason. The Hegelian l notion ' is thus the completion of what is vaguely shadowed forth in the Monad of Leibniz, and more especially in the Monas Monadum, in which all is (however unsatisfactorily) brought to unity. For the notion implicitly contains all in itself, and all is realized through its logical (not temporal) development. Like the Monad, the notion is not in time any more than it is in space ; it comprehends both. The difference is that by Leibniz the development is conceived as a continuous growth or increase in a certain fundamental quality (clearness and distinctness of perception), while by Hegel it is represented as a dialectic movement from that which is relatively abstract, through its correlative abstraction (or its ' negation ') to that which, comprehending or uniting both, is relatively concrete. For Leibniz develop- ment is from small to great (witness, for instance, his petites perceptions) ; for Hegel development is from frag- ments to wholes, or rather from the vague and undeter- mined to the definite and determined. Accordingly what Leibniz means by saying that the Monad (or its qualities) cannot go out of itself and cannot be entered or influenced from outside, would by Hegel be expressed as the doctrine that thought or self-consciousness is reality, the universe, and that accordingly it can neither go beyond itself nor have anything beyond it. It may sunder itself ideally, but it cannot really go out of itself, for there is no ' out of itself/ In the same way the Monad may ideally be sundered into active and passive elements (entelechy and materia prima^, but it can really give nothing and it can really receive nothing. The difference 190 INTRODUCTION at this point between the attitude of Hegel and that of Leibniz is due to the fact that while Leibniz interprets * perception ' as that which it is in its lowest form (mere 1 representation ' or ' expression '), and regards conscious- ness and self-consciousness as developments from it by increase or addition, Hegel interprets ' representation ' or relation in general as being essentially that which it is in its highest form (self -consciousness), and regards the lower forms as * abstract ' or incomplete foreshadowings, undeveloped expressions of it. For Hegel as for Leibniz the universe is organic throughout. No part of it is actually other than self-determined, for the unity of the whole and its parts is absolutely complete, so that no part can be conceived as having any reality by itself. Leibniz holds that the Monads must be conceived on the 'analogy' of the soul. Hegel insists on a unity which is closer than mere analogy, and which, at the same time, expresses itself in the greatest possible variety ; he regards self-consciousness, explicitly or implicitly, as the reality of every part, every member or organ, of the whole. In short, it may be said that in Leibniz's account of simple substance we have the first suggestion of the transition from substance to subject (as the ultimate reality of things), which is brought to completion by Hegel '. Lotze's Reconstruction of the Hypotheses of Leibniz. It seemed to Lotze that the ' bold Monism ' of Hegel * undertook far more than human powers can achieve,' although 'its leading idea by no means loses its value through the great defects in its execution V This ' leading idea ' was in Lotze's opinion the * reconciliation of oppo- sites,' the overcoming of the contradictions in thought by bringing all knowledge to systematic unity. But Lotze's 1 Cf. generally Caird, Critical Philosophy of Kant, vol. ii. bk. i. ch. 12, especially pp. 62 sqq. See also Monadology, § 30. 2 Lotze, Metaphysic, bk. i. ch. 7, § 88 (Eng. Tr., vol. i. p. 206). ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ'S PHILOSOPHY IQI interpretation of * thought ' is very different from that of Hegel. Although he expressly repudiated the suggestion that he is to be counted as a follower of Herbart, Lotze's position as regards thought and the reconciling of its contradictions is more akin to the view of Herbart than to that of Hegel. Like Herbart he regards thought as essentially analytic, as interpreting rather than constituting reality, and the work of science or philosophy is thus not that of laying down an absolute all-comprehensive system, expressing the whole evolution of reality, but that of unifying our knowledge, resolving the contradictions that appear in common experience. Thought cannot pierce to the inner nature of things, cannot understand them so thoroughly that it could make them. To use a distinc- tion which has become a commonplace among writers on natural science, thought can describe but it cannot explain*. It can give an account of what happens, can express in the form of general laws the relations between things, so as to be able to calculate occurrences, and can possibly reduce these laws to one general system ; but it cannot tell what the things themselves really are, how they originally came into being, and why they are so and not otherwise. In short, thought is governed solely by the principle of contradiction ; the principle of sufficient reason (in Leibniz's sense) is beyond it. ' Reality is infinitely richer than thought. . . . We know that in fact the nature of reality yields a result to us unthinkable. It teaches us that being and not-being are not, as we could not help thinking them to be, contradictory predicates of every subject, but that there is an alternative between them, arising out of a union of the two which we cannot construct in thought. This explains how the extravagant utterance could be ventured upon, that it is just contradiction 1 For a fuller account of this distinction, see Merz, History of European Thought in the Nineteenth Century, vol. i. pp. 337, 382, 383, notes. Venn (Empirical Logic, ch. 21) minimizes the distinction, holding explanation to be generalization. I Q2 INTRODUCTION which constitutes the truth of the real. Those who used it regarded that as contradictory which was in fact superior to logical laws — which does not indeed abrogate them in their legitimate application, but as to which no sort of positive conjecture could possibly be formed as a result of such application1.' The revolt of Lotze against the idealism of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel was due to the bad treatment which the ' Philosophy of Nature ' had received at their hands. The self-confidence of a thought which had found itself absolute resulted in a Naturphilosophie which despised facts ; and Lotze, as a scientist, felt it necessary to bring down thought from 'the high horse of idealism,' and assign to it the humble work of observation and descrip- tion. ' The study of medicine, which I had chosen as my life-work, made it necessary for me to acquire a knowledge of natural science, and hence (in brief) I came to see how completely untenable is a great part of the views of Hegel, or rather the whole of them, in the form in which they are put2.' It was to a large extent through his medical studies that Lotze arrived at one of the chief doctrines of his philosophy, viz. the universality of mecha- nism as an account of the relations between phenomena. 'The father of modern physiology,' Johannes Mtiller (1801-1858), had changed the whole aspect of biological science by extending the conception of mechanism to all the phenomena of life 3. Lotze took a further step in the same direction when he defined mechanism as * the con- nexion of all those universal laws, according to which every individual in the created world acts upon every other4.' The sphere of mechanism is thus extended so as 1 Lotze. Metaphysic, bk. i. ch. 6, § 76 (Eng. Tr., vol. i. pp. 178, 17.9). See the whole chapter, in which the views of Leibniz and Herbart are discussed. 8 Lotze, Streitschrift, p. 7. 3 Merz, History of European Thought in the Nineteenth Century, vol. i. pp. 216 sqq.; cf. Lotze, Metaphysic, bk. ii. ch. 8, §§ 224 sqq. (Eng. Tr., vol. ii. p. 128). 4 Streitschrift, p. 57. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 193 to include the phenomena not merely of inorganic and organic bodies, but also of mind. ' The function of mechanism in the construction of the world is, without an exception, universal in its extent1.' The conception of mechanism governs all science, for the principle of all our thinking is the principle of contradiction, which can only accept what is given in experience and systematize its laws. But Lotze protests strongly against the view that mechanism gives us a final explanation of the reality of the world. The laws of science are laws of phenomena ; they do not account for the things themselves. We may say that the essence of a thing is to stand in relations to other things. But the thing itself is more than the relations, and mechanism gives us an account of the rela- tions only. Thus while * the function of mechanism in the construction of the world is universal in its extent, it is entirely subordinate in its importance*.' As mere thought is by itself inadequate to reality, so mechanism (the system of laws which it is the work of science to discover and express) is not an eternally necessaiy system, constituting the very nature of things, but is merely the way in which the ultimate idea, the good, has freely chosen to realize itself3. Not thought, but goodness is ultimate, and ' the establishing of mechanism is the first ethical deed of the Absolute. The fact that there is a kingdom of universal laws appears to me to be compre- hensible only in a world whose ultimate principle is an ethical one ; another world (if I were to try to form for myself the notion of it, which is for me absurd) might, it 1 Kleine Schriften, iii. 310. 2 Loc. cit., cf. Microcosmus, Introduction (Eng. Tr., vol. i. p. xvi). 3 ' Mechanism is but the collection of all the instrumental forms in which God has willed that created beings shall act on one another with their unknown natures, and that all their states shall be welded into the endless chain of a world-history. This view explores the sphere of means, not the sphere of ends to which these minister.' Microcosmus, bk. iii. Conclusion. (Eng. Tr., vol. i. P- 398.) 0 194 INTRODUCTION appears to me, have arisen — a world without this thread of consecutiveness, without this veritas in the sense of the old metaphysicV Accordingly for Lotze the ultimate reality is a personal God, who sets before Himself the highest moral ends, and has established the ' absolutely valid system of laws which rules the world ' as the best means of securing these ends. Thought is a means of attaining to complete experience ; mechanism is a means of realizing the best. l There is no " nature of things " outside of God,' limiting the sphere of His choice. But on the other hand, His choice is not arbitrary, but is governed by His perfect idea of what is absolutely best. In this the influence of Leibniz is so manifest that it does not surprise us to find Lotze writing to the younger Fichte : i I went willingly through the splendid gateway which he [Herbart] is convinced that he has been able to erect as an entrance to his metaphysic ; the gateway of the Leibnitian Monad-world V Thus, according to Lotze, we are constrained to conceive the real world as a world of Monads, which are ultimately one in nature. In addition to mechanism, or the system of laws governing (or ex- pressing) the relations between things, there are the things themselves, the facts, which may be conceived as Monads. And both of these (the laws and the facts) presuppose a universal and all-pervading substance, which is merely a postulate of thought, but is a reality for feeling, and which (being intelligible only through the idea of a personal Deity) realizes the highest moral ends in the sphere of the facts by means of the laws. Things are to be thought of as Monads, because nature is to be con- ceived as animated throughout; all things are endowed with 'modes of sensation and enjoyment3.' Otherwise 1 Streitschrift, p. 57. 2 Ibid. p. 7. 8 Microcosmus, bk. iii. ch. 4, § 3 (Eng. Tr., vol. i. p. 360). Cf. Lotze's early writing— Pensees dun Idiote sur Descartes, Spinoza et Leibnitz. (Kleine Schriften, vol. iii. p. 564.) ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 195 we should have to regard all nature as merely machinery for the drama of human consciousness — a view which could never satisfy our 'longings' and i cravings.' But this monadology or t hypothesis of unextended atoms' can never; for Lotze, be more than a hypothesis. Thought can never determine its truth, because it is a hypothesis regarding the nature of things, and thought has to do only with their relations. The monadology is i a concep- tion of whose essential truth we are convinced, yet to which we can hardly expect any further concession than that, among the dreams of our imagination, it may be one of those which do not contradict actual facts V Lotze is here manifestly more in harmony with Kant than with Leibniz 2. And he further differs from Leibniz in maintaining that the Monads are not completely isolated from one another, so that each contains its own relations within itself. If Leibniz's doctrine be true, * while none of the members [of the real world] condition each other, everything goes on as if they all did so ; accordingly, while it does not really form a whole, yet to an intelli- gence directed to it, it will have the appearance of doing so ; and, in one word, its reality consists in a hollow and delusive imitation of that inner consistency which was pronounced to be, as such, the ultimate reason why its realization was possible3.' Accordingly for Lotze 'every single thing and event can only be thought as an activity, constant or transitory, of the one existence, its reality and substance as the mode of being and substance of this one existence, its nature and form as a consistent phase in the unfolding of the same4.' The pre-established harmony of Leibniz is thus set aside by Lotze 5. Its place 1 Microcosmus, bk. iii. ch. 4, § 3 (Eng. Tr., i. 360; cf. i. 363). 2 For an excellent account of the general relation of Lotze to Kant, see Jones, Philosophy of Lotze, pp. 64 sqq. 8 Metaphysic, bk. i. ch. 6, § 79 (Eng. Tr., vol. i. p. 184). Cf. the whole context. * toe. cit. 5 'Only if the course of all, even of the most trivial, events were fixed by immutable predestination, could the assumption of O 2 196 INTRODUCTION is taken by the conception of mechanism, through which we describe the relations in which things are for thought. Such relations as those between the phenomena of the soul and the phenomena of the body can be described on purely mechanical principles : that is to say, the condi- tions of their connexion can be stated as laws. And the theory of a pre-established harmony is not required (not to say that it is insufficient) to explain how the phenomena of the soul have any connexion with those of the body — how, for instance, physical nerve-motion passes into psychical sensation. It is impossible for our thought to explain this ; but it is just as impossible for our thought to explain how one physical phenomenon is invariably connected with another physical phenomenon — how, for instance, the burning match is connected with the explod- ing gunpowder1. In neither case can thought do more than describe a connexion invariable in our experience. Science must be content with a ( practical occasionalism ' as distinct from the ' theoretical ' (i. e. absolute ontological) ; occasionalism ' of the Cartesians 2. Thus in Lotze we find the principles of the philosophy of Leibniz modified by Kantian influences. Like Leibniz, Lotze in his application of the principles of contradiction and of sufficient reason keeps them sharply apart from a pre-established harmony — not, indeed, explain anything, but— tolerably well describe the facts. ... It is only if individual things do not float independent or left to themselves in a vacuum across which no connexion can reach— only if all of them, being finite individuals, are at the same time only parts of one single infinite substance, which embraces them all and cherishes them all within . itself, that their reciprocal action, or what we call such, is possible.' Microcosmus, bk. ix. ch. i, § 5 (Eng. Tr., vol. ii. pp. 597, 598). Cf. Metaphysic, bk. i. ch. 5, §§63 sqq. (Eng. Tr., vol. i. p. 150). 1 ' As in our life we see the physical motions of external nature employed as stimuli to excite that in ourselves which is far higher — conscious sensation : so, we think, throughout the universe mechanical events are but the external tissue of regularly crossing stimuli, designed to kindle at innumerable points, within in- numerable beings, the true action of a more intelligent life.' Microcosmus, bk. iii. Conclusion. (Eng. Tr., vol. i. p. 399.) 2 Streitschrift, p. 96. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 197 one another. But, unlike Leibniz, he regards the principle of contradiction as, indeed, universally applicable but completely subordinate in importance. According to Leibniz, mechanism in the real world is subordinate to teleology, efficient to final causes. But at least the co- ordinate priority of the principle of contradiction is secured by the conception of the ' possible ' things or * essences,' the realm of ideas, in the understanding of God. Lotze, on the other hand, does away with this realm of ' possi- bles,' making the 'principle of the best' absolutely supreme, allowing the choice of God to be independent even of the principle of contradiction, independent of all save the ideal of absolute ethical worth. A violation of the law of contradiction is an absurdity for us ; but God might conceivably (if it had been the most perfect means to the realizing of the best) have made a world in which the law of contradiction did not hold. But as Leibniz gave no clear explanation of the relations between the two principles of contradiction and sufficient reason, so Lotze does not explain the subordination of the one to the other, but maintains that any such explanation is beyond the reach of human thought. From early years Lotze was familiar with the works of Leibniz, and his writings continually suggest Leibnitian ways of looking at things. But, though an inheritor of Leibniz's ideas, he could not ' take over ' the philosophy as a whole. ' I have, indeed, in general never had the presumption to declare myself the successor of Leibniz, in the sense of being his heir . . . but I must have the presumption to admit that I could only have entered into possession of this inheritance cum beneficio inventarii1.' Other Influences of Leibniz. It would be impossible briefly to indicate the full influence of the philosophy of Leibniz in other directions. 1 Kleine Schriften, vol. iii. p. 342. 198 INTRODUCTION While the academic writers on philosophy missed much of his best thought, its spirit was felt in the literature of Germany through the works of Lessing and Herder1. Nor was Leibniz's thinking altogether without effect upon English literature ; for, though the doctrine is sadly straitened into platitude, that sense of the varied whole- ness and harmonious system of things which pervades the Theodicee is cleverly expressed in the Essay on Man by the phrases of which Pope was a master ". Again, with regard to the influence of Leibniz upon natural science, reference may be made to the way in which his idea that the organism is a group of smaller organisms, has been in various forms developed by naturalists like Buffon 3, and has finally gained something like scientific verification in the cell-theory of Schwann. Johannes Muller recognized this by giving to the cells the somewhat inappropriate name of * organic monads V Modern psychology also, in the attention it directs to 'sub-conscious' processes and in its analysis of sensations and perceptions into elements which are individually unnoticed (e. g. the * over-tones ' of Helmholtz and the ' local signs ' of Lotze), owes much to 1 See Merz's Leibniz (Blackwood's Philosophical Classics), pp. 195 sqq. There are also traces of the influence of Leibniz in the works of Schiller, who is said to have written his poem Die Freundschaft when his mind was full of ideas suggested by the reading of Leibniz. This is the poem from which Hegel in his Geschichte d. Phil., vol. i. p. 91 (ed. 1840), quotes the well-known lines ' Freundlos war der grosse Weltenmeister,' &c. The poem belongs to Schiller's ' First Period.' 8 See Introduction to the edition by Mark Pattison (Clarendon Press). Bolingbroke said of Pope that he was • a very great wit, but a very indifferent philosopher.' 3 Cf. Buffon's Histoire Naturelle, &c. (1787), vol. iv. p. 22 : 'Living beings contain a large number of living and active molecules. The life of the animal or of the plant appears to be only the result of all the activities, of all the little individual lives (if I may so speak) of each of these active molecules, whose life is underived [primitive] and appears incapable of destruction.' 4 Weismann regards the unicellular organism as immortal. Cf. Essays upon Heredity, &c. (Eng. ed. by Poulton, SchOnland, and Shipley, pp. 25 and 27). For a good account of the relation of Leibniz's philosophy to modern scientific thought, see Watson, Comte, Mill and Spencer, pp. 126 sqq. ESTIMATE OF LEIBNIZ S PHILOSOPHY 199 Leibniz's far-reaching suggestion of the unconsciousness perceptions. For this suggestion also (if for little else) Hartmann's Philosophy of the Unconscious is indebted to Leibniz \ And further, in these days when we are so persistently assured that 'the real is the individual,' Monadology may be said to be in the air, and we need not be surprised to find that, in one form or another, it has its adherents in theologians like Dorner, philosophical teachers like Groom Robertson, and expositors like Dill- mann. The fruits of the philosophy of Leibniz are as widely scattered as its roots were far spread. The materials of his philosophy were derived from every sphere of thought, from every generation of thinkers, and he gave to the future as liberally as he borrowed from the past. * Nicht Vielwisser war er, sondern, soweit der Mensch es kann, All- und Ganzwisser, und sein Erfassen, sein Erkennen, war stets zugleich schopferischer Act2.' 1 See Tr. by Coupland, vol. i. pp. 16 sqq. 2 ' He was learned not merely in many things but, so far as a man can be, in all and everything, and his very comprehending or acquiring of knowledge was also an act of creating.' E. Du Bois-Eeymond, Leibnisische Gedanken in der neueren Naturwissenschaft, in his Eeden, Erste Folge, p. 33. 200 INTRODUCTION APPENDIX A. EXPLANATION OF THE PRE-ESTABLISHED HARMONY BY A SPECIAL INSTANCE. IN a letter to Arnauld (1687) (G. ii. 113) Leibniz gives an account of the way in which his theory may be applied to a particular case (that of the relation between a pin-prick in the body and pain in consciousness).. 'We have now to inquire how the soul is conscious of the motions of its body, since we can see no way of explaining by what channels the activity of an extended mass can pass into an indivisible being. Ordinary Cartesians declare that no explanation of this union can be given. The authors of the hypothesis of occasional causes think that it is nodus vindice dignus, cui Deus ex Machina intervenire debeat. For my part I explain it in a natural way. From the notion of substance or concrete [accompli] being in general, which declares that its present state is always a natural consequence of its preceding state, it follows that the nature of each individual substance, and consequently of every soul, is to express the universe. Each has been from the first created such that, in virtue of the laws of its own nature, it must happen that it is in harmony with what takes place in bodies, and especially in its own body. We need not then be surprised to find that it has the power of representing to itself the pin- prick, when this takes place in its body. And, to complete my explanation on this point, we have : — State of the body at moment A. State of the soul at moment A. State of the body at the following State of the soul at moment B. moment B. (Pin-prick.) (Pain.) 1 As, then, the state of the body at moment B follows from the state of the body at moment A, so the state of the soul B is a consequence of A, the preceding state of the same soul, according to the notion of substance in general. Now the APPENDIX A 201 states of the soul are naturally and essentially expressions of the corresponding states of the world, and especially of the bodies which for the time belong to the soul. Accordingly, since the pin-prick is a part of the state of the body at the moment B, the representation or expression of the pin-prick (i. e. the pain) will be a part of the soul at the moment B ; for as one motion follows from another motion, so one representa- tion follows from another representation in a substance whose nature is to be representative. Thus the soul must needs be conscious of the pin-prick, when the laws of relation require it to express more distinctly a more observable change in the parts of its body. It is true that the soul is not always distinctly conscious of the causes of the pin-prick and of its coming pain, when these are still hidden in the representation of the state A, as when we sleep or in some other way are unaware of the approach of the pin. But that is because the motions of the pin at that time make too little impression, and though we are already in some way affected by all these motions and their representations in our soul, and thus have within us the representation or expression of the causes of the pin-prick, and consequently the cause of the representation of the same pin- prick, that is to say, the cause of the pain— yet we can unravel them from the multitude of other thoughts only when they become noticeable. Our soul reflects only upon the more marked phenomena, which stand out from the others ; not thinking distinctly of any, when it thinks equally of all. After this explanation, I cannot imagine where anybody can find the least shadow of farther difficulty, unless he is prepared to deny that God can create substances which are so made from the beginning that each in virtue of its own nature is after- wards in harmony with the phenomena of all the others. Now nobody seems to deny this possibility, and since we see that mathematicians represent in a machine the motions of the heavenly bodies (as when Jura poll rerumque fidem legesque deorum Cuncta Syracosius transtulit arte senex, which we can do to-day much better than Archimedes could in his day), why could not God, who excels them infinitely, from the beginning create representative substances in such a way that they express by their own laws, according to the natural change of their thoughts or representations, all that is to 202 INTRODUCTION happen to every body? This seems to me not only easy to conceive, but also worthy of God and of the beauty of the universe, and in a way necessary, since all substances must have a mutual harmony and connexion and all must express in themselves the same universe and the universal cause, which is the will of their Creator, and the decrees or laws which He has established in order to make them fit into one another as well as possible. Thus this mutual correspondence of different substances (which, speaking with metaphysical strictness, can- not act upon one another, and yet are in harmony as if one did act upon another) is one of the strongest proofs of the existence of God or of a common cause which each effect must always express according to its point of view and its capacity of expression. Otherwise the phenomena of different minds would not harmonize, and there would be as many systems as substances ; or rather, it would be entirely a matter of chance if they were sometimes in harmony.' APPENDIX B. FORMATION OF THE IDEA OF SPACE. IN § 47 of the fifth letter to Clarke, Leibniz gives an account of the origin of the idea of space. 'I will here show how men come to form to themselves the notion of space. They consider that many things exist at once and they observe in them a certain order of co-existence, according to which the relation of one thing to another is more or less simple. This order is their situation or distance. When it happens that one of those co-existent things changes its relation to a mul- titude of others, without their changing their relations among themselves ; and that another thing, newly come, acquires the same relation to the others as the former had ; we then say it is come into the place of the other ; and this change we call a motion in that body, wherein is the immediate cause of the change. And though several, or even all the co-existent things should change according to certain known rules of direction and velocity, we can always determine the relation of APPENDIX B 203 situation which each acquires with reference to every other, and we can even determine the relation which any other [co-existent] would have [to this], or which this would have to any other, if it had not changed or if it had changed otherwise. And supposing or feigning that among those co-existents there is a sufficient number of them, which have undergone no change, then we may say that those which now have to those fixed existents a relation such as that which others formerly had to them, have the same place which these latter had. And that which comprehends all these places is called space, which shows that in order to have an idea of place, and consequently of space, it is sufficient to consider these relations and the rules of their changes, without needing to fancy any absolute reality outside of the things whose situation we consider. And, to give a kind of definition : place is that which we say is the same for A and for B, when the relation of co-existence between B and C, E, F, G, &c., is in perfect agreement with the relation of co-existence which A formerly had with the same C, E, F, Gr, &c. ; provided that in C, E, F, G-, &c., there has been no cause of change Place is that which is the same in different moments to different existent things, when the re- lations of co-existence between each and certain other existents, which are supposed to continue fixed from moment to moment, agree entirely together. And fixed existents are those in which there has been no cause of change in the order of their co- existence with others, or (which is the same thing) in which there has been no motion. In short, space is that which results from places taken together. And here it is right to consider the difference between place and the relation of situation which is in the body occupying the place. For the place of A and B is the same ; whereas the relation of A to the fixed bodies is not exactly and individually the same as the relation which B (that comes into its place) will have to the same fixed bodies : these relations are only in agreement. For two different objects, as A and B, cannot have exactly the same individual affection ; it being impossible that the same individual accident should be in two objects or pass from one object to another. But the mind, not satisfied with mere agreement, looks for an identity, for something which should be really the same, and conceives it as outside of the objects : and this is what we here call place and space. But this can only be an ideal thing, involving a certain order, in which 204 INTRODUCTION the mind conceives relations to be applied.' (E. 768 a; G. vii. 400.) I have made some slight alterations in Clarke's translation for the sake of clearness. As to other details of Leibniz's doctrine of space, cf. Eraser's ed. of Locke's Essay, vol. i. pp. 158 and 1 86. APPENDIX C. THE MEANING OF CAUSE. IN a draft of a letter to Arnauld (1686) (G. ii. 68) Leibniz expounds his view of cause as follows-: — 'The hypothesis of concomitance is a consequence of my notion of substance. For, in my view, the individual notion of a substance includes all that is ever to happen to it, and it is in this respect that concrete things [etres accomplis = res completae ?] differ from those which are not so. Now, the soul being an individual substance, its notion, idea, essence or nature must include all that is ever to happen to it ; and God, who sees it perfectly, sees in it all that it will ever do or suffer and all the thoughts it will have. Accordingly, since our thoughts are nothing but the consequences of the nature of our soul and arise in it in virtue of its notion, it is useless to seek in it the influence of any other particular substance, besides that such an influence is absolutely inexplicable. It is true that certain thoughts come to us when there are certain bodily motions, and that certain bodily motions happen when we have certain thoughts ; but that is because each substance expresses the entire universe in its own way, and that expression of the universe which is a motion in the body is perhaps a pain in relation to the soul. But we attribute activity [action} to that substance whose expression is the more distinct, and we call it cause. Thus when a body passes through water, there is an infinity of motions of the parts of the water, such as there must be in order that the place which the body leaves may be filled up again by the shortest way. We say that this body is the cause of the motions, because by its means we can explain distinctly what happens ; but if we consider what is physical APPENDIX C 205 and real in the motion, we may equally well suppose that the body is at rest and that everything else moves, in accordance with the hypothesis, since the whole motion in itself is only a relative thing, viz. a change of position [situation] which we do not know how to explain with mathematical exactness ; but we do attribute it to a body by means of which all is distinctly explained ' [i. e. so far sufficiently explained, though not with mathematical exactness]. 'And in fact, taking all the phenomena little and great, there is only one hypothesis which serves to explain the whole distinctly. And we may indeed say that, although this body may not be an efficient physical cause of these effects, its idea is at least, so to speak, their final, or, if you like, archetypal [exemplaire] cause in the understanding of God. For, if we wish to find whether there is anything real in the motion, let us imagine that God wills directly to produce all the changes of situation in the universe exactly as if this vessel were producing them in passing through the water ; is it not true that there would actually happen exactly the same thing ? For it is impossible to assign any real difference. Thus, in metaphysical strict- ness, we have no more reason to say that the vessel compels the water to make this great number of ripples by means of which the place of the vessel is filled up, than to say that the water is compelled to make all these ripples and that it compels the vessel to move in conformity with it; but, except by saying that God has willed directly to produce so great a number of motions all tending to this one thing, we can give no reason for it, and as it is not reasonable to have recourse to God for the immediate explanation of matters of detail, we have recourse to the vessel, although actually, in an ultimate analysis, the agreement of all the phenomena of the various substances comes only from this, that they are all productions of one and the same cause, to wit, God; and consequently each individual substance expresses the re- solution which God has taken with regard to the whole universe It is quite right to say that my will is the cause of the motion of my arm and that a solutio continui in the matter of my body is the cause of pain, for the one expresses distinctly what the other expresses more confusedly, and activity {action} is to be attributed to the substance of which the expression is more distinct.' (p. 71.) 206 INTRODUCTION APPENDIX D. LEIBNIZ'S LOGIC. IN the Nouveaux Essais, bk . iv. ch. 1 1 , § 14 (E. 379 a ; G. v. 428 ), there is an interesting passage explaining in more detail a part of the logic of Leibniz. It contains some remarkable anticipa- tions of more modern views. ' Propositions of fact also may become general in a way, but it is by induction or observation ; so that it ' [the general proposition of fact] * is nothing but a multitude of similar facts, as when we observe that all quicksilver evaporates by the force of fire ; and this is not a perfect generality, because we do not see its necessity. General propositions of reason are necessary, although reason also furnishes some which are not absolutely general and are only probable, as for instance, when we presume that an idea is possible, until a more strict investigation reveals its contrary. There are, finally, mixed propositions, which are drawn from premises, of which some come from facts and observations, while others are necessary propositions : and such are numerous geographical and astronomical conclusions about the globe of the earth and about the course of the stars, which conclusions are obtained by combining the observations of travellers and astronomers with the theorems of geometry and arithmetic. But as, according to the usage of logicians, the conclusion follow* the weaker of the premises, and cannot have more certainty than they, these mixed propositions have only the certainty and generality which belong to observations. As to eternal truths, it is to be noted, that at bottom they are all conditional and say in effect : Granted such a thing, such another thing is. For instance, when I say, Every figure which has three sides will also have three angles, I say nothing but this, that supposing there is a figure with three sides, this same figure will have three angles. I say this same figure, and it is in this respect that categorical propositions, which can be stated unconditionally APPENDIX D 207 (although fundamentally they are conditional), differ from those that are called hypothetical, such as the following: If a figure has three sides, its angles are equal to two right angles. In this latter case we see that the antecedent (namely, the figure with three sides) and the consequent (namely, the angles of the three-sided figure are equal to two right angles) do not have the same subject, as they had in the preceding case in which the antecedent was — This figure has three sides, and the conse- quent— The said figure has three angles. Nevertheless the hypothetical might often be transformed into a categorical by a slight change in the terms, for instance, if in place of the preceding hypothetical I were to say : The angles of every three- sided figure are equal to two right angles. The Scholastics have argued much de constantia subjecti, as they called it, that is to say, how a proposition regarding a subject can have a real truth, if the subject has no existence. The fact is that the truth is only conditional and says that, supposing the subject ever exists, it will be found to be so-and-so. But it will still be asked : On what is this connexion founded, since there is within it reality which does not deceive ? The reply will be, - that it is in the connexion of ideas. But it will be asked again : Where would these ideas be, if no mind existed, and what would then become of the real foundation of this certainty of eternal truths ? That leads us at last to the ultimate founda- tion of truths, namely, that supreme and universal spirit, which cannot but exist, whose understanding, to speak truly, is the region of eternal truths, as St. Augustine has recognized and says in a vivid way1. And lest it should be thought unnecessary to have recourse to this, it is to be noted that these necessary truths contain the determining reason and regulative principle of existences themselves, and, in a word, the laws of the universe. Thus these necessary truths, being anterior to the existence of contingent beings, must have their foundation in the existence of a necessary substance. It is here that I find the original of the ideas and truths which are graven in our souls, not in the form of propositions, but as sources from which application and opportunity will produce actual statements.' 1 The reference may be to Augustine, De Genesi ad Litteram, bk. v. cap. 13 sqq. (Migne's ed., iii. 331 sqq.), or to Enarratio in Psalmum xlix. (Migne's ed., iv. 576 sqq.). Cf. De diversis Quaestionibus, Q. xlvi. § 2 (Migne's ed., vi. 30). 208 INTRODUCTION APPENDIX E. KANT ON HIS KELATION TO LEIBNIZ. THE Wolffians endeavoured to show that Kant's philosophy was merely a degenerate product of Leibnitian thought. In reply to Eberhard, Kant in 1790 wrote an interesting account of his own relation to Leibniz— Uber eine Entdeckung, nach der alle neue Kritik der reinen Vernunft durch eine altere entbehrlich gemacht werden soil. See Rosenkranz, i. pp. 478 sqq. ; Harten- stein, iii. 390 sqq. 'The metaphysic of Leibniz contains three great original principles: (i) the principle of sufficient reason, especially in so far as it shows the insufficiency of the principle of contra- diction for the knowledge of necessary truths ; (2) the monad- ology ; (3) the doctrine of the pre-established harmony (i) Is it to be believed that Leibniz desired his principle of sufficient reason to be understood objectively (as a law of nature), when he attached a great importance to this principle as an addition to the principles of earlier philosophy? It is indeed so universally known and (within proper limits) so manifestly clear, that the poorest intellect could not imagine it had made a new discovery in finding it. Thus it is that critics, who have misunderstood it, have greatly ridiculed it. But for Leibniz this principle was merely a subjective one, that is to say, a principle having reference merely to a critique of reason. For what is meant by saying that, in addition to the principle of contradiction, there must be other first principles? It is as much as to say that, according to the principle of contradiction only that can be known which is already contained in the notion [Begriff] of the object ; but if we say anything more about the object, something must be added to this notion, and thus we must find a special principle different from that of contradiction, for our assertions must have their own special reason. Now propositions of thia APPENDIX E 209 latter kind are now-a-days called synthetic, and thus Leibniz means nothing but this : " In addition to the principle of contradiction (as the principle of analytic judgments), there must be another principle, namely that of synthetic judgments." This was a new and remarkable suggestion of investigations in metaphysics which had not yet been undertaken (and which have actually been undertaken only recently) (2) Is it to be believed that so great a mathematician as Leibniz held that bodies are composed of Monads (and consequently that space is made up of simple parts) ? He referred not to the corporeal world, but to its substratum imperceptible [uner- kennbar] to us, namely, the intelligible world which belongs merely to the idea of reason, and in which doubtless we must represent to ourselves as made up of simple substances everything which we think therein as compound substance. He likewise appears, like Plato, to attribute to the human mind an original, although at present only obscure, intellectual intuition [AnscTiauen] of these supersensible realities. But in this he did not refer to the things of sense, which he attributes to intuition [Anschauung] of a special kind, of which we are capable only in relation to things we can really know [fur uns mogliche ErJcenntnisse], and he regards the things of sense as mere phenomena (in the strict use of the term), as specific forms of intuition peculiar to us. With regard to this we must not allow ourselves to be perplexed by his explanation of sensation as a confused kind of perception, but must rather substitute for it another explanation more in harmony with his main purpose; for otherwise his system would be in- consistent with itself. To take this defect as a deliberate and careful speculation on the part of Leibniz (as copiers, in order to make their copy exactly the same as the original, reproduce its mistakes of form and language) can hardly be credited to the disciples of Leibniz as a service done to the fame of their master. Similarly, if it is taken too literally, a wrong inter- pretation is given to the view of Leibniz regarding the innate- ness of certain notions, by which he means a fundamental faculty to which the a priori principles of our knowledge are referable : he makes use of this idea merely as against Locke, who recognized no other than an empirical origin of these principles. (3) Is it possible to believe that, by his pre- established harmony between soul and body, Leibniz meant a mutual conformity of two beings entirely independent of P 210 INTRODUCTION one another as regards their nature and incapable of being brought into connexion through their own forces? That would have been to proclaim idealism ; for why should the existence of bodies in general be admitted, if it is possible to regard everything that takes place in the soul as the effect of its own powers, which it would exercise even if it were entirely isolated? The soul and the substratum (entirely unknown to us) of the phenomena which we call bodies are indeed two quite different beings, but these phenomena them- selves, as mere forms of their intuition [Anschammg] depending upon the nature of the subject (the soul), are mere perceptions [Vorstellungen]. Hence the connexion between understanding and sense in the same subject can be understood according to certain a priori laws, as well as the necessary and natural dependence of sense upon external things, without sacrificing external things to idealism. For this harmony between under- standing and sense, in so far as it renders possible a priori the knowledge of universal laws of nature, criticism has given as a reason that without this harmony no experience is pos- sible But we can give no reason why we have just such a kind of sense and an understanding of such a nature that through their combination experience is possible ; and further we can find no reason why they, as completely heterogeneous sources of knowledge, always so completely harmonize in rendering possible experiential knowledge in general and more especially (as the Critique of Judgment shows) in rendering possible an experience of nature, under its manifold special and merely empirical laws, regarding which the understanding teaches us nothing a priori. Neither we nor any one else can explain how this harmony is as com- plete as if nature had been arranged expressly to suit our power of comprehension. Leibniz called the principle of this union (especially with reference to the knowledge of bodies and in particular of our own body as a middle term in this relation) a pre-established harmony. Manifestly he did not in this way give an explanation of the union, nor did he profess to explain it. He merely pointed out that we must regard the order established by the supreme cause of ourselves as well as of all things outside of us as involving a certain conformity to end. This purpose is regarded as present at creation (pre-established) ; yet as a pre-established agreement, not between things taken as outside one another, but only APPENDIX E 211 between our mental powers of sense and understanding, ac- cording to the special constitution of each in relation to the other. In the same way criticism teaches that, in order to a knowledge of things a priori, these powers must stand in relationship to one another ;n the mind. That this was what Leibniz really meant, although he did not clearly develop it, appears from this, that he extends the application of the pre-established harmony beyond the relation between soul and body to the relation between the kingdom of nature and the kingdom of grace (the kingdom of ends in relation to the supreme end, i. e. man under moral laws). Here the harmony is to be thought of as a harmony between what follows from our notions of nature and what follows from our notions of freedom, and thus as a harmony between two completely different powers in us, having completely dissimilar principles, and not between two different things taken as external to one another. And this harmony, as the Critique teaches, can in no way be comprehended from the nature of created things [Weltwesen] but, as it is for us an essentially contingent har- mony, it can only be understood by referring it to an intelligent cause of the world.' p 2 THE MONADOLOGY THE MONADOLOGY1. 1714. PREFATORY NOTE. THE Monadology is one of the latest of the works of Leibniz, having been written at Vienna in 1714, two years before his death. On this last visit of his to Vienna he had met the soldier prince Eugene of Savoy, who (probably through Queen Sophia Charlotte of Prussia) had heard of the one great work Leibniz had hitherto published, the Theodicee, which appeared in 1710. Having read the Theodice'e, Prince Eugene begged Leibniz to write for him a condensed statement of the main principles of his philosophy, and having obtained this, in the form either of what we now call the Monadology or of the Principles of Nature and of Grace, he was so delighted with it that he kept it like a jewel in a case, so that his friend, Count Bonneval, wrote to Leibniz, perhaps with a touch of humorous exaggeration : — ' He keeps your writing as the priests at Naples keep the blood of St. Januarius ; he lets me kiss it and imme- diately shuts it up again in its casket.' (Guhrauer, ii. 287.) The Monadology was written in French; but it was not published in its original form until 1840, when Erdinann, who had discovered the MS. in the Royal Library at Hanover, printed it in his edition of the philosophical works of Leibniz. German and Latin translations of it appeared in 1720 and 1721, and it was for a long time combined with the Principles of 1 Erdinann gave the name ' La Monadologie ' to this work when lie published it in 1840. Kohler published a German version of it in 1720, under the title: Lehrsatze uber die Monadologie, &c. Dutens gives a Latin translation of the German and entitles it : Principia philosophiae seu theses in gratiam Principis Eugenii. The original MSS. have no title. 2l6 THE MONADOLOGY Nature and of Grace, there being some doubt as to which of the two was the treatise written for Prince Eugene. The two writings are similar in scope and intention, and were probably written about the same time. Gerhardt holds that the work written for Prince Eugene was not the Monadology but the Principles of Nature and of Grace. (See G. vi. 483 and prefatory note to the Principles of Nature and of Grace in this edition.) The Principles of Nature and of Grace certainly appears to be the earlier of the two. As to its contents, the Monadology is to be regarded, not as an introduction to the philosophy of Leibniz, but rather as a condensed statement of the principles expressed in many philo- sophical papers, and expounded, after a somewhat desultory fashion, in the Theodicee. Leibniz himself indicated this fact by putting on the margin of his manuscript of the Monadology a series of references to sections of the Theodicte in which his views are more fully expressed. Thus, as Erdmann says, the Monadology is (in the German sense) an ' Encyclopaedia ' of the philosophy of Leibniz, and the full understanding of it presupposes some general knowledge of his thinking. It is not possible rightly to understand it at a first reading. The Monadology expounds a Metaphysic of Substance, and it may for convenience be regarded as consisting of two main divisions, in the first of which an account is given of the essen- tial nature of all the substances, created and uncreated, which constitute the reality of the universe, while the second division explains the mutual relations through which they form one world. §§ I to 48 make up the first of these divisions, the second consisting of §§ 49 to 90. In the first division three principal parts may be discriminated; (a) §§ 1-18, in which the nature of Created 'Monads is explained; (b) §§ 19-30, in which three great classes of Created Monads are discriminated ; and (c) §§ 31-48, in which transition is made from the highest class of Created Monads (the self-conscious) to the Uncreated Monad (God) through the two great principles of Reason, that of Contradiction and that of Sufficient Reason. Thus a philo- sophic view is taken of the whole universe, considered as a hierarchy of individual beings. The second division of the Monadology, in which the mutual relations of substances are more fully explained, may also be subdivided into three prin- cipal parts : (a) §§ 49-60, expounding the general principles 217 of the inter-relation of substances through the hypothesis of the Pre-established Harmony and the doctrine of 'the best of all possible worlds' ; (6) §§ 61-82, explaining in more detail the relations of particular classes of substances to one another, and dealing with questions of organism and of the relations of soul and body, including birth and death, &c. ; and (c) §§ 83-90, in which the whole system of relations is brought to unity in God, the distinction and harmony between efficient and final causes (which had been found to be the basis of the distinction between body and soul), being supplemented by an analogous distinction and harmony between the ' physical realm of nature and the moral realm of grace, that is to say, between God, considered as Architect of the machine of the universe and God considered as Monarch of the divine City of spirits.' This brief analysis is to be taken merely as a suggestion of the line of thought in the Monadology ; the texture of the work is so close that it is impossible to make perfectly satisfactory divisions in it. The translation is made from the text given by M. Boutroux, who has collated the MSS. at Hanover and corrected some errors of Erdmann. The Monadology is given in E. 705 sqq. ; G. vi. 607 sqq. 1. The Monad, of which we shall here speak, is nothing but a simple substance, which enters into compounds. By 'simple 'is meant * without parts.' (Theod. 10.) 2. And there must be simple substances, since there are compounds ; for a compound 2 is nothing but a collection or aggregatum of simple things3. 2 There is a slight but interesting difference between this and the corresponding passage in the Principles of Nature and of Grace (see p. 406). Leibniz speaks here of ' a compound ' in general (le com- pose') : in the other passage he uses the expression ' compound substance ' (la composed). In both cases he must be understood to mean 'body,' which, he -elsewhere tells us, is not a substance, strictly speaking (Introduction, Part iii. pp. 96 and in). Accord- ingly, the expression here is more exact than that in the Principles of Nature and of Grace ; but the difference illustrates the looseness of Leibniz's terminology in this connexion. 3 If the ' simple things ' are, like the Monads, non-quantitative, can we attach any intelligible meaning to ' compounds/ which are mere aggregates of them ? Does not an aggregate always imply 2l8 THE MONADOLOGY 3. Now where there are no parts 4, there can be neither extension nor form [figure] nor divisibility. These Monads are the real atoms of nature and, in a word, the elements of things 5. 4. No dissolution of these elements need be feared, and there is no conceivable way in which a simple sub- stance can be destroyed by natural means. (Theod. 89.) 5. For the same reason there is no conceivable way in which a simple substance can come into being by natural means, since it cannot be formed by the combination of parts [composition] 6. elements which are quantities, however small ? Leibniz elsewhere makes it perfectly clear that nothing quantitative can ever be absolutely simple, and thus there seems a weakness in his reasoning at this point. The difficulty is fundamental and affects the whole of Leibniz's system : it is, indeed, the crux of every Individualist or Atomist philosophy. Leibniz's hypothesis of a ' living [formef] atom,' a ' fertile simplicity,' a ' centre which expresses (or repre- sents) an infinite circumference ' (Reponse aux Reflexions de Bayle, 1702, E. 187 a ; G. iv. 562), is the suggestion of a way out of Atomism ; but it does not take us entirely out of the wood. We have still, in the spirit of much of Leibniz's philosophizing, to ask ourselves the question — « Are not " simple " and " compound " purely relative terms, so that to search for an absolutely simple thing is to explore blind alleys ? ' Kant shows us the blind alleys in his second Antinomy (Critique of Pure Reason, Meiklejohn's Tr., p. 271). See also the interesting analysis and criticism of Kant's arguments in Hegel's Wissenscftaft der Logik. bk. i. div. 2, ch. i. sect. A, note. Cf. Hegel's Geschichte der Philosophie, vol. iii. p. 525 (Eng. Tr., p. 449). * i. e. where there are no spatial distinctions. 5 Cf. New System, § 3. Ordinary physical atoms have form and extension ; and, though they may not be physically divisible, yet they must be ideally divisible ad infinilum, inasmuch as they occupy space. Thus for Leibniz all merely physical atoms are unreal. Cf. Lange's History of Materialism, bk. i. sect. 4, ch. iv. (Eng. Tr., vol. ii. pp. 124 sqq.). 6 According to Leibniz a thing is produced by nature only when it comes into being gradually, bit by bit. But the Monads, having no parts, cannot come into being by the adding of part to part. Yet it may be pointed out that every Monad has an internal development, which is gradual. It is not born perfect, fully realized. Why, then, should it not come into being by natural means ? THE MONADOLOGY 219 6. Thus it may be said that a Monad can only come into being or come to an end all at once ; that is to say, it can come into being only by creation and come to an end only by annihilation, while that which is compound comes into being or comes to an end by parts7. 7. Further, there is no way of explaining how a Monad can be altered in quality or internally changed 8 by any other created thing ; since it is impossible to change the place of anything in it or to conceive in it any internal motion which could be produced, directed, increased or diminished therein, although all this is possible in the case of compounds, in which there are changes among the parts9. The Monads have no windows, through which anything could come in or go out. Accidents cannot separate themselves from substances nor go about outside of them, as the 1 sensible species ' of the Scholastics used to do 10. Thus 7 Consider, by way of analogy and contrast, what Spinoza says regarding the eternity of the human mind, Ethics, v. prop. 23. Spinoza dispenses with the idea of creation. But according to Leibniz there are created Monads, whose creation is, nevertheless, not an event in time, for time and space have to do merely with phenomena, and the Monads are not in time and space, but con- dition them. Cf. § 47 and Introduction, Part iii. p. 101. 8 The meaning is that by other things the Monad can neither be altered as to its nature, i.e. changed into something else, nor even affected in those changes of state which it can undergo without a change of nature. 9 It is implied that all changes in bodies are reducible to traits- position of parts, and ultimately to changes in the amount alid direction of motion. See Introduction, Part iii. pp. 89 sqq.''r 10 Leibniz seems here to have in view partly the doctrines of Thomas Aquinas and partly the scholastic theories which werer , based on the system of Democritus. The l species ' are images or immaterial representations of material qualities. According to Thomas Aquinas, the accidents of things are known to us by means of sensible species, or particular images, while we know the essences of things by means of intelligible species or general I images. The scholastic theory in general may be said to be t^ the sensible or intelligible ' species ' in us have something common with the accidents or essences in things, though 220 THE MONADOLOGY neither substance nor accident can come into a Monad from outside11. 8. Yet the Monads must have some qualities, otherwise they would not even be existing things 12. And if simple substances did not differ in quality, there would be is a considerable variety of more or less vague opinion as to the nature of the relation. Leibniz is evidently thinking of a theory (not that of Thomas Aquinas), according to which sense-perception means that particles are detached from the body perceived and pass into the percipient, in whom they are reconstructed into images or representations of qualities in the thing perceived. Images of this kind were called efScwAa by Democritus. Of. Ritter and Preller, Historia Philosophies Graecae, § 155. Atomists felt bound to explain the action of body upon soul by the suggestion of some kind of influxus physicus. Descartes has a parallel passage to this of Leibniz, in which he says that he ' desires to rid people's minds of all these little images, flying through the air, called intentional species, which give s'o much work to the imagination of philo- sophers.' Dioptrique, Discours I. Cf. ether passages quoted by Veitch in his Translation of Descartes' s Method and Meditations, note 2 — l Idea.' u Kant pointed out that a thing may have < intensive' as well as * extensive ' quantity, i. e. quantity which is not divisible into spatial parts as well as quantity which is so divisible. A stone descending from a height loses a certain * intensive quantity ' without losing any of its spatial parts. And thus a simple sub- stance may, in a certain sense, lose and receive quality. Cf. Critique of Pure Reason (Hartenstein, ii. 178 ; Rosenkranz, ii. 145 ; Meiklejohn's Tr., p. 125), Kant argues that the simplicity of the soul (i.e. the absence of parts in it) does not necessarily prove its indestructibility, for, though it has no parts, it may lose con- sciousness and the rest of its essential qualities (Hartenstein, ii. 318; Rosenkranz, ii. 792; Meiklejohn's Tr., p. 245). Compare Kant's 'intensive quantity' with Leibniz's degrees of Perception and Appetition. 12 After this sentence Leibniz originally wrote, and then deleted, these words : ' And if simple substances were nonentities [news], compounds also would be reduced to nothing.' This emphasizes the point that a being without quality is indistinguishable from nothing ; cf. Hegel's Logic, Wallace's Tr., pp. 158 sqq. Quantity always presupposes quality ; see Introduction, Part ii. pp. 27 sqq. Leibniz seems also to imply that each Monad must have more than one quality. On the other hand, Herbart (1776-1841), whose Monadology owes much to that of Leibniz, and who calls his Monads ' primary qualities ' (Urqualitaten'), holds that a substance cannot be perfectly simple unless it has only one ultimate quality. THE MONADOLOGY 221 absolutely no means of perceiving any change in things. For what is in the compound can come only from the simple elements it contains, and the Monads, if they had no qualities, would be indistinguishable from one another, since they do not differ in quantity13. Consequently, space being a plenum, each part of space would always receive, in any motion, exactly the equivalent of what it already had, and no one state of things would be dis- cernible from another14. 13 Kant would say that they may differ in ' intensive quantity' ; see note n. L'eibnfz makes the distinction between quality and quantity as sharp as the Aristotelian distinction between iroTov and troffov. Yet in some respects his Law of Continuity suggests a different view. " E. reads * one state of things would be indistinguishable from another.' Cf. Epistola ad Des Bosses (1706) (G. ii. 295) r. 'If we were to admit, as the Cartesians desire, the plenum and the uniformity of matter, adding to these motion alone, it would follow that nothing would ever take place among things but a substitution of equivalents, as if the whole universe were reduced to the motion of a perfectly uniform wheel about its axis or, again, to the revolu- , tions of concentric circles, each made of exactly the same materials. [The result of this would be that it would not be possible, even for an angel, to distinguish the state of things at one moment from their state- at another. For there could be no variety in the phe- nomena. ^Accordingly, in addition to figure, size, and motion, we must allow certain Forms, whence there arises a distinction among the phenomena of matter ; and I do not see whence these Forms are to be taken, if they are to be intelligible, unless it be from Entelechies.' To avoid a possible misunderstanding, it should be noted that for Leibniz, the Monads are not in space, which is a relation between phenomena ; see Introduction, Part iii. p. 101. Cf. Epistola ad Des Bosses (1712) (E. 682 b ; G. ii. 450): 'Space is the order of co-existing phenomena, as time is the order of successive phenomena. There is no nearness or distance, whether spatial or absolute, among Monads, and to say that they are collected, together in one point or dispersed throughout space, is to make use of certain fictions of our mind, by which we try to represent to ourselves in imagination what cannot be imagined but only understood.' Kant, misled by the position of Wolff, does not rightly interpret Leibniz's view of space, which he discusses in the Critique of Pure Reason, Hartenstein, ii. 256 sqq. ; Kosenkranz, ii. 216 sqq. ; Meiklejohn's Tr., pp. 191 sqq., especially p. 199. Cf. Introduction, Part iv. pp. 1 68 sqq. 222 THE MONADOLOGY 9. Indeed, each Monad must be different from every' other. For in nature there are never two beings which are perfectly alike and in which it is not possible to find an internal difference, or at least a difference founded upon an intrinsic quality [denomination] 15. 10. I assume also as admitted that every created being, and consequently the created Monad, is subject to change, and further that this change is continuous in each16. 15 This is the principle of the ' identity of indiscernibles ' ; see Introduction, Part ii. p. 36. Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. ii. ch. xxvii. § 3 (E. 277 b ; G. v. 214). For Kant's criticism see Critique of Pure Reason, Hartenstein, ii. 267 ; Eosenkranz, ii. 229 ; Meiklejohn's Tr., p. 202. Probably the first statement of the principle is to be found in the writings of Nicholas of Cusa (14,31-1464). He says that 4 there cannot be several things exactly the same [aequalia~}, for in that case there would not be several things, but the same thing itself. Therefore all things both agree with and differ from one another.' (De Venatione Sapientiae, 23.) Cf. De docta ignorantia, iii. i : 'All things must of necessity differ from one another. Among several individuals of the same species there is necessarily a diversity of degrees of perfection. There is nothing in the universe which does not enjoy a certain singularity, which is to be found in no other thing.' His theories are full of suggestions of Leibniz. Cf. Falckenberg, History of Modern Philosophy, English Tr.. pp. 20 sqq. Reference may also be made to a very interesting article by Zimmer- mann, Nicolaus Cusanus als Vorlaufer Leibnitzens (Wien. Akad. Sitsungs- berichte, vol. 8, p. 306). There is no mention of Nicholas of Cusa in any of Leibniz's philosophical writings ; but in a letter to the Acta Eruditorum (1697) Leibniz refers to him as a mathematician (cf. Dutens, iii. 345). — Intrinsic qualities are those which things have in themselves, e.g. figure, motion, &c., while extrinsic qualities are those which arise from their relations to other things, e.g. their being perceived, desired, &c. Cf. Port-Royal Logic, part i. ch. ii. (Baynes's Tr. , p. 37) : ' There are some modes which may be called internal, because they are conceived to be in the substance, as round, square ; d,nd others which may be called external, because they are taken from something which is not in the substance, as loved, seen, desired, which are names taken from the actions of another — and this is what is called in the schools external denomination.' 16 There is constant change in created substances, even though there may appear to be no change. What appears to us as absence of change is really a very small degree of change. We have here an application of the Law of Continuity. THE MONADOLOGY 223 ii. It follows from what has just been said, that the natural 17 changes of the Monads come from an internal principle, since an external cause can have no influence upon their inner being. (Theod. 396, 400.) 1 2 18. But, besides the principle of the change, there must be a particular series of changes [un detail de ce qui change], which constitutes, so to speak, the specific nature and variety of the simple substances. 13. This particular series of changes should involve a multiplicity in the unit [unite] or in that which is simple. For, as every natural change takes place gradually, something changes and something remains unchanged19; and consequently a simple substance must be affected and related in many ways, although it has no parts 20. 17 i. e. other than miraculous changes or than such change as may be implied in the creation or annihilation of a Monad. 18 At the beginning of § 12 Leibniz originally wrote : 'And gener- ally it may be said that force is nothing but the principle of the change.' He seems afterwards to have felt that force was not a deep enough notion to be an adequate expression of the principle which, in §§ 14 and 15, he describes under the names of Perception and Appetition. 19 The Law of Continuity. Everything is continually changing, and in every part of this change there is both a permanent and a varying element. That is to say, at any moment everything both 'is' and 'is not,' everything is becoming something else — some- thing which is, nevertheless, not entirely ' other.' ao In illustration of this and the following sections, cf. Eeponse aux Reflexions de Bayle (1702) (E. 186 b ; G. iv. 562) : « The state of the soul, as of the atom, is a state of change, a tendency. The atom tends to change its place, the soul to change its thought : each changes of itself in the simplest and most uniform way, that its state allows. Whence comes it, then (I shall be asked), that there is so much simplicity in the change of the atom ' [which is taken as being always motion in a straight line at a uniform speed] ' and so much variety in the changes of the soul ? The reason is that the atom (as it is supposed to be, for there is no such thing in nature), although it has parts, has nothing which causes any variety in its tendency, because it is supposed that these parts do not change their relations ; while on the other hand the soul, though it is perfectly indivisible, has a composite tendency, that is to say, it contains a multitude of present thoughts, of which each tends to 224 THE MONADOLOGY 14. The passing condition, which involves and repre-* sents a multiplicity in the unit [unite~] or in the simple substance, is nothing but what is called Perception 21, which is to be distinguished from Apperception or Consciousness, as will afterwards appear. In this matter the Cartesian view is extremely defective, for it treats as non-existent those perceptions of which we are not consciously aware22. This has also led them to believe that minds [esprits] alone are Monads, and that there are no souls of animals nor other Entelechies. Thus, like the crowd, they have failed to distinguish between a prolonged unconsciousness and absolute death23, which has made a particular change, according to the nature of its content, and which all are present together in the soul; in virtue of the soul's essential relation to all the other things in the world. It is because they do not have this relation that the atoms of Epicurus have no existence in nature. For there is no individual thing, which is not to be regarded as expressing all others ; and consequently the soul, in regard to the variety of its modifications, ought to be likened to the universe, which it represents according to its point of view, and even in a way to God, whose infinity it represents finitely, because of its confused and imperfect perception of the infinite, rather than to a material atom.' Cf. Appendix Fr p. 272. 21 Cf. Epistola ad Des Bosses (1706) (E. 438 a ; G. ii. 311): 'Since perception is nothing else than the expression of many things in one, all Entelechies or Monads must necessarily be endowed with perception.' Also Lettre a Arnauld (1687) (G. ii. 112) : 'Because of the continuity and divisibility of all matter, the least motion has its effect upon neighbouring bodies, and consequently upon one body after another ad infinitum, in a gradually lessening degree ; and thus our body must in some way be affected by the changes in all other bodies. Now, to all the motions of our body there corre- spond certain more or less confused perceptions of our soul, and accordingly our soul also will have some thought of all the motions in the universe, and in my opinion every other soul or substance will have some perception or expression of them.' See Introduction, Part ii. p. 33. 22 Cf. Method, Part 5, and Meditations, 2 and 6. See also Principia Philosophiae, i. 48, and cf. Introduction, Part iii. p. 126. The Car- tesian view is that animals and plants are purely ine'chanical structures or living automata, parts of extension, entirely separate from thought. 23 * Sleep, which is an image of death, trances, the burying of THE MONADOLOGY 225 them fall again into the Scholastic prejudice of souls entirely separate [from bodies], and has even confirmed ill-balanced24 minds in the opinion that souls are mortal25. a silkworm in its cocoon, the resuscitation of drowned flies by means of a dry powder sprinkled upon them (when they would remain quite dead, if this were not done), the resuscitation of swallows which make their winter quarters among the reeds, where they are found without any appearance of life, the cases of men frozen to death, drowned, or strangled, who have been brought to life again ... all these things serve to confirm my opinion that these different conditions differ only in degree, and if we have not the means of bringing about resuscitation from death in other forms, it is either because we do not know what ought to be done or because, though we do know it, our hands, our instruments, and our remedies cannot accomplish it, especially when dissolution takes place too quickly and has gone too far. Accordingly we must not content ourselves with the notions which the common people may have about life and death, when we have both analogies and (what is more) solid arguments which prove the contrary. Lettre a Arnauld (1687) (G. ii. 123). 2t E. reads mal touches ; G. and Boutroux, mal tournes. 25 Descartes regards the immortality of the soul as ultimately dependent on the will of God. See the Abrege prefixed to the Meditations [Synopsis in Veitch's translation]. Cf. Eeponses aux Deuxiemes Objections, 7. Leibniz thus criticizes the view of Descartes : ' The immortality of the soul, as it is established by Descartes, is of no use and can give us no kind of consolation. For, granting that the soul is a substance and that no substance perishes, the soul then will not be lost, as, indeed, nothing is lost in nature ; but, like matter, the soul will change in appearance and, as the matter of which a man is made has at other times belonged to plants and animals, in the same way the soul may be immortal, indeed, but it will pass through innumerable changes and will have no re- collection of its former states. But this immortality without recollection is ethically quite useless ; for it is inconsistent with reward and punishment. What good, sir, would it do you to become king of China, on condition that you forget what you have been ? Would it not be the same as if God, at the moment He destroyed you, were to create a king in China ? ' (G. iv. p. 300.) From his own point of view, however, Descartes can say: 'Al- though all the accidents of the mind be changed — although, for example, it think certain things, will others, and perceive others, the mind itself does not vary with these changes ; while, on the contrary, the human body is no longer the same if a change take place in the form of any of its parts.' Abrege des Meditations. It 226 THE MONADOLOGY 15. The activity of the internal principle which pro- duces change or passage from one perception to another _may be called Appetition. It is true that desire [I'appetit] cannot always fully attain to the whole perception at which it ajms, but it always obtains some of if and attains to new perceptions26. 1 6. We have in ourselves experience of a multiplicity in simple substance, when we find that the least thought of which we are conscious involves variety in its object27. Thus all those who admit that the soul is a simple substance should admit this multiplicity in the Monad ; and M. Bayle 28 ought not to have found "any difficulty seems to me not improbable that in the last words of this section Leibniz may have in view, among others, the wandering Irishman, John Toland (1670-1722), author of Christianity not Mysterious, who was in Berlin in 1702 and had a brief correspondence with Leibniz, in which the question of the immortality of the soul is referred to. Leibniz writes to the Princess Sophia Charlotte with something like a kindly contempt of Toland's readiness to take either side of a question. See G. vi. pp. 508 sqq. Of. Principles of Nature and of Grace, § 4. -6 See Introduction, Part ii. p. 33. Cf. Principles of Nature and of Grace, § 2. In many of his writings Leibniz uses the word ' tendencies ' (tendances} for appetitions. Force is a form of appetition or tendency, i. e. it is not merely what actually appears as motion, &c., but it includes something potential. And it is not really, but only ideally, an influence of one substance upon another. Cf. appetition, in respect of likeness and difference, with Spinoza's Conatus. 27 Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. ii. ch. 2 (E. 227 a ; G. v. 109). 88 Pierre Bayle, the son of a Protestant clergyman, was born at Carlat in Languedoc, in 1647. He was educated at the University of Toulouse, where, under the influence of Jesuit teachers, he became a Roman Catholic. But his Roman Catholicism was not lasting and, having returned to his original faith, he avoided the censures of the Church by going to Geneva. After some years of wandering he became a Professor of Philosophy in the University of Sedan (1675). But owing to the < free- thinking ' of Bayle and others Louis XIV summarily suppressed this Protestant University in 1681, and Bayle went, as Professor of History and Philosophy, to a newly established institution at Rotterdam. In 1684 he founded the Nouvelles de la RepuUique des Lettres, a monthly review of new books, &c., to which there is frequent reference in the writings of Leibniz. THE MONADOLOGY 227 in this, as he has done in his Dictionary, article ' Kora- rius'29. 1 7. Moreover, it must be confessed that perception and that which depends upon it are inexplicable on mechanical In 1693, ostensibly on political as well as theological grounds, he was deprived of his professorship, and he afterwards devoted him- self to his Dictionnaire Historique et Critique (1695-96), which was the precursor of the Encyclopaedias and the Encyclopaedist movement in the following century. Among other writings he also published a tract against religious persecution and a reply to Maimbourg's libels upon Calvinism. He died in 1706. The Theoclicee of Leibniz is to a large extent devoted to answering the arguments of Bayle, who maintained the impossibility of reconciling faith with reason. There .is much difference of opinion as to whether Bayle was sincere in his combination of philosophical scepticism with an appeal to faith in matters of religion. Probably in this regard he meant to follow the example of Descartes. Leibniz seems to have believed in the sincerity of Bayle's religious faith. He always writes of Bayle with the greatest respect, saying of him (Theod. § 174): ' Ubi lene, nemo melius,' and again, after his death: 'We must believe that Bayle is now enlightened with that light, which is refused to earth, since, according to all appearance, he has always been a man of good will.' 29 Like the greater part of Bayle's Dictionary, the article ' Rorarius' may be said to consist mostly of foot-notes. Jerome Rorarius (1485-1566), an Italian, was Papal Nuncio at the Court of Ferdinand of Hungary. He was so great an admirer of the Emperor Charles V that, on hearing a learned man speak of him as inferior to Otho and to Frederick Barbarossa, he was moved to write a treatise maintaining that men are less rational than the lower animals. This treatise (Quod animalia bruta ratione utantur melius homine) was not published until about 100 years after it was written, when Descartes's views regarding the souls of animals were under discussion. Bayle accordingly makes the name of Rorarius the occasion of a full consideration of the question, in the course of which he expounds and criticizes the opinions of Leibniz. Bayle thinks it a pity that the position of Descartes is so difficult to maintain and so unlikely to be true ; for otherwise it would be very helpful to the true faith. That is to say, the Cartesian view is regarded as confirming belief in the immortality of the soul by making a very great distinction between man and 'the brutes which perish.' But it seems to Bayle that Leibniz (whom he calls ' one of the greatest minds in Europe ') has made some suggestions (in regard to the solution of the general problem) which are worthy of being developed. These suggestions are contained in the New 228 THE MONADOLOGY grounds, that is to say, by means of figures and motions. And supposing there were a machine, so constructed as to think, feel, and have perception, it might be conceived as increased in size, while keeping the same proportions, so that one might go into it as into a mill. That being so, we should, on examining its interior, find only parts which work one upon another, and never anything by which to explain a perception 30. Thus it is in a simple substance, and not in a compound or in a machine, that perception must be sought for31. Further, nothing but this (namely, perceptions and their changes) can be found in a simple substance. It is also in this alone that all System, which was published in the Journal des Savans of June 27, 1695 (the year before the second vol. of Bay4e's Dictionary appeared). Bayle's criticism is directed mainly against the pre-established harmony and the spontaneous development of all their states by simple substances. Cf. Appendix F. p. 272. 30 That is to say, even if we had microscopes powerful enough to reveal to us, on a large scale, all the intricacies of nerve-cell and nerve-fibre in the brain, we should still never get beyond figures and motions. Cf. Commentatio de Anima Brutorum (1710)^. 463 a ; G. vii. 328) : ' If in that which is organic there is nothing but mechanism, that is, bare matter, having differences of place, magnitude and figure ; nothing can be deduced and explained from it, except mechanism, that is, except such differences as I have just mentioned. For from anything taken by itself nothing can be deduced and ex- plained, except differences of the attributes which constitute it. Hence we may readily conclude that in no mill or clock as such is there to be found any principle which perceives what takes place in it ; and it matters not whether the things contained in the " machine " are solid or fluid or made up of both. Further we know that there is no essential difference between coarse and fine bodies, but only a difference of magnitude. Whence it follows that, if it is inconceivable how perception arises in any coarse "machine," whether it be made up of fluids or solids, it is equally inconceivable how perception can arise from a finer "machine"; for if our senses were finer, it would be the same as if we were perceiving a coarse " machine," as we do at present.' See also New Essays, Introduction, p. 400. (G. v. 59 ; E. 203 a.) 31 Mechanism always means partes extra paries. This is character- istic of all compounds, but not of any simple substances. Thus it can never be said that matter thinks. Matter pre-supposes a thinking or at least a 'perceiving' principle. THE MONADOLOGY 229 the internal activities of simple substances can consist. (Theod. Pref. [E. 474 ; G. vi. 37].) ( . 1 8. All simple substances or created Monads might be •'called Entelechies 32, for they have in them a certain per- fection (ZXOVO-L TO ZvT€\€ to be complete or absolute. Leibniz's use of the term differs considerably from that of Aristotle. €VT€\exeia in Aristotle is the state of perfection or realization in which IWpycto, as a process, ends, rovvop-a. iy^pytia At'yercu Kara TO epyov, /cat avvTflvei irpos TT)V tvTeXt\fiav. Melaph. 0, 8, ic>5oa 22. But the distinction between Iz/TfAexfia and evtpyeia in Aristotle is not by any means a sharp one. Thus he defines the soul (fax?]} as €VTt\(xft<*- "n TrpujTrj awfMTOS (pvaiKov dvvdp.fi farjv ZXOVTOS. De Anima, ii. i. But elsewhere he calls it ovffia Kal tvepyfia owpaTos TIVOS. Metaph. H, 3, io43a 35. First entelechy is related to second entelechy as kiriarrip.^ (implicit) is related to Oewpeiv (explicit). Thus the soul is denned as first or implicit entelechy because it exists in sleep as well as awake. The entelechy of Leibniz, how- ever, is to be understood as an individual substance or force, containing within itself the principle of its own changes. It i» called entelechy, not because it is a state of perfect realization, but because it contains in germ an infinity .of perfections, which it tends to develop. It is thus not so much the final developed condition of a thing, opposed to its potentiality (Swapis -or vkrj), but it rather implies the tendency or virtuality, of which Leibniz speaks as something intermediate between the bare potency (puis- sance) and the fully developed activity (acte) of the Scholastics. Cf. Introduction, Part iii. pp. 91, 105. ' The Forms of the Ancients or Entelechies are nothing but forces.' Lettre au Pere Bouvet, E. 146 a. Cf. Trendelenbui'g, De Anima, pp. 295, 320. In the eighth book of Aristotle's Metaphysics there is a remark of much interest, when considered in relation to Leibniz : rj ovaia €v OUTCWS, a\\' oi>x wj \cyovcri TtvfS olov poi/ds TIS ovffa r) (nty/J-rj, dAA.' €vrf\e\fia teal (pvffis TIS ctcdaTr). H, 3, 1044* 7. povds is, of course, used here in its original sense of a unit. 33 That is to say, not merely machines, such as those made by man, but entirely self-moving machines or machines which contain within themselves the ground or principle of all their states or conditions, in as complete independence of all else as if there were nothing in the universe but God and themselves. Monads alone are automata in this sense. Corporeal automata, in so far as they 230 THE MONADOLOGY 19. If we are to give the name of Soul to everything which has perceptions and desires [appetits] in the general sense which I have explained, then all simple substances or created Monads might be called souls ; but as feeling \le sentiment] is something more than a bare perception, I think it right that the general name of Monads or Entelechies should suffice for simple substances which have perception only, and that the name of Souls should be given only to those in which perception is more distinct, and is accompanied by memory34. 20. For we experience in ourselves a condition in which we remember nothing and have no distinguishable per- ception ; as when we fall into a swoon or when we are overcome with a profound dreamless sleep. In this state the soul does not perceptibly differ from a bare Monad ; but as this state is not lasting, and the soul comes out of it, the soul is something more than a bare Monad. (Theod. 64.) 21. And it does not follow that in this state the simple substance is without any perception. That, indeed, cannot be, for the reasons already given ; for it cannot perish, and it cannot continue to exist without being affected in some way, and this affection 35 is nothing but its perception. But when there is a great multitude of little perceptions, in which there is nothing distinct, one is stunned ; as when one turns continuously round in the are corporeal, cannot be said to have this avrapKaa. Cf. § 64. Spinoza speaks of the soul as * acting according to certain laws and us if it were a kind of spiritual automaton/ De Intellectus Emenda- tione, 85 ; Bruder's ed., ii. 34. 34 Memory is thus the sign of consciousness as distinct from unconscious perception. This is in harmony with the view, em- phasized by modern writers, that conscious sensation pre-supposes memory, because we can know one sensation only when it has been brought into comparison with others. Leibniz in one of his early writings suggestively remarks that body is 'momentary mind, i. e. mind without memory ' (mens momentanea, seu carem recordatione). Theoria Motus Abstracti (1671) (G. iv. 230). 35 Leibniz originally wrote * variation.' THE MONADOLOGY 231 same way several times in succession, whence comes a giddiness which may make us swoon, and which keeps us from distinguishing anything 36. Death can for a time put animals into this condition 37. 22. And as every present state of a simple substance is naturally a consequence of its preceding state, in such a way that its present is big with its future 38 ; (Theod. 350.) 23. And as, on waking from stupor, we are conscious of our perceptions, we must have had perceptions imme- diately before we awoke, although we were not at all conscious of them ; for one perception can in a natural way come only from another perception, as a motion can in a natural way came only from a motion 39. (Theod. 401-403.) 24. It thus appears that if we had in our perceptions nothing marked and, so to speak, striking and highly- flavoured, we should always be in a state of stupor. And this is the state in which the bare Monads are. 25. We see also that nature has given heightened perceptions to animals, from the care she has taken to provide them with organs, which collect numerous rays of light, or numerous undulations of the air, in order, by uniting them, to make them have greater eifect 40. Some- 36 Leibniz's point is that in such states as these we are still mani- festly in certain peculiar relations to the external world, although consciousness has, for the time, become so slight as to be imper- ceptible. 37 Cf. Honadology, § 14, note 23. 38 Cf. §§78 and 79. 39 In virtue of the principle of sufficient reason, every perception must have a cause, which can be nothing but another perception (see § 17) ; and if the antecedent perception did not immediately precede the consequent, there would be a breach of continuity in the existence of the soul. Ultimately, of course, motions are them- selves perceptions ; but they are confused perceptions, of such a kind that their relations to one another can be stated according to mechanical laws, which, however, are abstract and pre-suppose, for their full explanation, the system of final causes or the laws of perception in general. 40 Cf. Helmholtz, Popular Scientific Lectures, vol. i. p. 186. See also Principles of Nature and of Grace, § 4. 232 THE MONADOLOGY thing similar to this takes place in smell, in taste and in touch, and perhaps in a number of other senses, which are unknown to us 4l. And I will explain presently 42 how that which takes place in the soul represents what happens in the bodily organs. 26. Memory provides the soul with a kind of consecu- tiveness 43, which resembles [imite] reason, but which is to be distinguished from it. Thus we see that when animals have a perception of something which strikes them and of which they have formerly had a similar perception, they are led, by means of representation in their memory, to expect what was combined with the thing in this pre- vious perception, and they come to have feelings similar to those they had on the former occasion. For instance, when a stick is shown to dogs, they remember the pain it has caused them, and howl and run away44. (TJieod. Discours de la Conformite, &c., § 65.) 2 7. And the strength of the mental image which im- presses and moves them comes either from the magnitude or the number of the preceding perceptions. For often a strong impression produces all at once the same effect as a long-formed habit, or as many and oft-repeated ordinary perceptions45. 41 Cf. Lubbock, Ants, Bees and Wasps, ch. 8, especially pp. 220 and 225. 42 See §§ 61 and 62. 43 Consecutio, concatenation or sequence of perceptions. Leibniz is referring to what would now be called association of ideas. Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. ii. ch. n, § n (E. 237 b; G. v. 130), and bk. ii. ch. 33 (E. 296 a ; G. v. 252). In the latter of these chapters (' On the Association of Ideas ') he is thinking mainly of a ' non- natural connexion of ideas/ as in the case of strange prejudices or superstitions. 41 Does Leibniz in this section, as some critics maintain, over- look his * Pre-established Harmony ' and unconsciously adopt tho ordinary point of view, which implies that substances do really act upon one another and are not each the cause of all its own experiences ? ^ 45 Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. ii. ch. 33 (E. 296 a ; G. v. 252! 'And as the reasons ' [of the connexion of things] ' are often unknown to i THE MONADOLOGY 233 28. In so far as the concatenation of their perceptions is due to the principle of memory alone, men act like the lower animals, resembling the empirical physicians46, whose methods are those of mere practice without theory. Indeed, in three-fourths of our actions we are nothing but empirics. For instance, when we expect that there will be daylight to-morrow, we do so empirically, because it has always so happened until now. It is only the astronomer who thinks it on rational grounds47. 29. But it is the knowledge of necessary and eternal truths that distinguishes us from the mere animals and gives us Reason and the sciences, raising us to the know- ledge of ourselves and of God 48. And it is this in us that is called the rational soul or mind [_esprit\. us, we must attend to particular instances in proportion to their frequency ; for then the expectation or recollection of another perception, usually connected with the perception we are ex- periencing, is reasonable ; especially in cases where we have to take precautions. But as the violence [vehemence] of a very powerful impression often produces all at once as much effect as the fre- quency and repetition of several moderate impressions could have done in the long-run, it happens that this violence engraves in the fancy an image as deep and as vivid as long experience could have done. Whence it comes that a chance but violent impression combines in our memory two ideas, which were already together there, and gives us the same inclination to connect them and to expect the one after the other, as if long custom had verified their connexion. Thus association produces the same effect, though the same reason does not exist. Authority and custom produce also the same effect as experience and reason, and it is not easy to free oneself from these inclinations/ Cf. New Essays, Introduction, p. 364. 46 Until the time of Galen (circa 150 A.D.), there were various sects of physicians. One of these was the sect of the Empirics, who laid stress upon observation of the * visible' antecedents of disease, &c. In later times the name of empiric fell into disrepute and was given to physicians who despised theoretical study and trusted to tradition and to their own individual experience. 47 Cf. New Essays, Introduction, p. 365, note 39. 48 The necessary and eternal truths are the first principles of all rational knowledge. They are innate in us. They are, in fact, the very principles of our nature, as of the universe, because it is of our essence to represent the whole universe. Thus conscious- 234 THE MONADOLOGY 30. It is also through the knowledge of necessary truths, and through their abstract expression, that we rise to acts of reflexion, which make us think of what is called J, and observe that this or that is within us : and thus, thinking of ourselves, we think of being, of .substance, of the simple and the compound, of the immaterial, and of God Himself, conceiving that what is limited in us is in Him without limits. And these acts of reflexion furnish the chief objects of our reasonings49. (Theod. Pref. [E. 469 ; G. vi. 27].) ness or knowledge of these truths is knowledge of ourselves, and it is at the same time knowledge of God, who is the final reason of all things. Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. i. ch. i, § 4 (E. 207 b ; G. v. 72). 'A pretty general agreement among men is an indication and not a demonstration of an innate principle ; but the exact and decisive proof of these principles consists in showing that their certainty come^ only from what is in us. ... It may be said that all Arithmetic and all Geometry are innate and are in us in a virtual manner, so that we could find them by attentively con- sidering aiid arranging what is already in our mind, without making use of any truth learned by experience or by external tradition, as Plato has shown in a dialogue ' [Meno, 82 sqq.] ' in which he introduces Socrates leading a child to abstruse truths by questions alone, without giving him any information.' Cf. Principles of Nature and of Grace, § 5. 49 Thus consciousness becomes self-consciousness (reflective con- sciousness) when we realize the eternal truths as eternal, that is to say, as the innate principles of our being and of the whole world. Substance is always a soul of some kind, because it must be something analogous to what we find in ourselves. Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. i. ch. i, § 21 (E. 211 b ; G. v. 70). 'Very often know- ledge of the nature of things is nothing but knowledge of the nature of our mind [esprit] and of those innate ideas, which there is no need to look for outside of it/ Cf. also § 23 (E. 212 b ; G. v. 71) : 'Intellectual ideas or ideas of reflexion are derived from our mind ; and I should like very "much to know how we could have the idea of being, were it not that we ourselves are beings and thus find being in ourselves.' We see here (in however imperfect a form) the germ of the Kantian transition from ' substance ' to 'subject' as the ultimate metaphysical reality. Cf. p. 190. Boutroux finds in this passage the indication of a succession of stages in the progress of self-conscious reflexion. The nature of God is the truth or ultimate reality of our nature. Thus in 1 reflexion, that is to say, in the return of the being towards its THE MONADOLOGY 235 v^ 31. Our reasonings are grounded upon two great princi- ples, that of contradiction, in virtue of which we judge false that which involves a contradiction, and true that which is opposed or contradictory to the false 50 ; (Theod. 44, 169.) 32. And that of sufficient reason, in virtue of which we hold that there can be no fact real or existing, no statement true, unless there be a sufficient reason, why it should be so and not otherwise, although these reasons usually cannot be known by us51. (Theod. 44, 196.) 33. There are also two kinds of truths, those of reason- source, which is God . . . we first of all come upon the ego, or the being which is in us, in so far as it is limited and distinct from other beings, and then upon being, substance and the immaterial, coming ever nearer to the Divine Essence itself. And finally, through perception which has thus become reflective and conscious, we reach the Infinite Being, whom, from the first, created beings are seeking confusedly and unwittingly. Then the circle, so to speak, closes upon itself : the created being identifies itself with the Creator in so far as He is in it ; the finite has done all that its nature allowed in the way of reproducing the infinite.' (Edition of La Monadologic, p. 156.) 50 Cf. Introduction, Part ii. pp. 58 sqq. Leibniz sometimes distinguishes between the principle of contradiction and that of identity (A = A). But he recognizes that they are ultimately one. Cf. Nouveaux Essals, bk. iv. ch. 2, § i (E. 339 a; G. v. 343). 'The principle of contradiction is in general : a proposition is either true or false. This contains two true statements ; (i) that the true and the false are not compatible in the same proposition or that a proposition cannot be true and false at the same time ; (2) that the opposites or negations of the true and the false are not compatible, or that there is no middle term between the true and the false, or rather that it is impossible for a proposition to be neither true nor false.' See Aristotle, Metaph. T, 3, ioo5b 19 and 7, ionb 23. 51 In his earlier writings Leibniz calls the sufficient reason the determining reason, meaning the reason which determines the exis- tence of this or that out of a number of possibilities, each of which involves no self-contradiction. As synonymous with the ' principle of sufficient 'reason,' he also sometimes uses the phrase, 'principle of fitness [convenance'] or of harmony.' He thus suggests that the sufficient reason of a thing is always to be found in its relations to other things, its place in the general system. We give the sufficient reason of anything when we show its ' compossibility ' with other 236 THE MONADOLOGY ing and those of fact 52. Truths of reasoning are necessary and their opposite is impossible : truthg of fact are con- tingent and their opposite is possible 53. When a truth is necessary, its reason can be found by analysis, resolving it into more simple ideas and truths, until we come to those which are , primary 5\ (T7ieod. 170, 174, 189, 280- 282, 367. Abrege, Object. 3.) things in addition to its abstract 'possibility.' The principle of sufficient reason is the principle of final cause. Leibniz's adoption of the word ' sufficient ' is supposed to have been suggested by its use in Mathematics in a sense similar to that in which we say that a certain magnitude ' satisfies ' a particular equation. 52 Cf. the Scholastic ratio cognoscendi and ratio essendi. 53 Cf. Theodicee, § 174 (E. 557 b ; G. vi. 217). 'It may be said of M. Bayle : Ubi bene, nemo melius, though it ciould not be said of him, as it was said of Origen: Ubi male, nemo pejus. . . . Yet M. Bayle adds at the end ' [of a passage, quoted by Leibniz in the previous section] 'words which somewhat spoil what he has so justly remarked. " Now what contradiction would there have been if Spinoza had died at Leyden ? Would nature have been less perfect, less wise, less powerful ? " He here confounds what is impossible, because it involves a contradiction, with what cannot happen, because it is not well fitted to be chosen. It is true that there would have been no contradiction in the supposition that Spinoza had died at Leyden and not at the Hague : it was perfectly possible. Accord- ingly, as regards the power of God, the matter was indifferent. But it must not be imagined that any event, however insignificant, can be regarded as indifferent in relation to God's wisdom and goodness.' 54 Leibniz does not give us a very clear idea of the relations of the two principles to the two kinds of truths. This is probably due to his hesitancy regarding the relations of the two principles to one another. In the Appendix to the The'odicee entitled Remarques ftur le livre de M. King, Leibniz says (E. 641 b; G. vi. 414): 'Both principles must apply not only to necessary, but also to contingent truths, and, indeed, that which has no sufficient reason must necessarily be non-existent. For it may in a manner be said that these two principles are included in the definition of the true and the false. Nevertheless when, by analyzing a suggested truth, we see that it depends upon truths whose opposite involves a contra- diction, we can say that it is absolutely necessary. But when, carrying our analysis as far as we like, we can never reach such elements of the given truth, it must be said to be contingent, and to have its origin in a prevailing reason, which inclines without necessitating.' But on the other hand, at a later date, Leibniz THE MONADOLOGY 237 34. It is thus that in Mathematics speculative Theorems and practical Canons are reduced by analysis to Definitions, Axioms and Postulates. 35. In short, there arejiimple ideas, of which no defini- tion can be given 55 ; there are also axioms and postulates, in a word, primary principles, which cannot be proved, and indeed have no need of proof ; and thesa are identical propositions56, whose opposite involves an express contra- diction. (Theod. 36, 37, 44, 45, 49, 52, 121-122, 337, 340-344.) {36) But there must also be a sufficient reason for con- tingent truths or truths of fact ^, that is to say, for the sequence or connexion of the things which are dispersed throughout the universe of created beings, in which the analyzing into particular reasons might go on into endless detail, because of the immense variety of things in nature and the infinite division of bodies 58. There is an infinity writes to Clarke (IIme Ecrit de Leibni?, E. 748 a ; G. vii. 355) : ' The principle of contradiction is by itself sufficient for the demon- stration of the whole of Arithmetic and Geometry, that is to say, of all mathematical principles. But in order to pass from Mathe- matics to Physics, another principle also is needed, the principle of sufficient reason.' See Introduction, Part ii. pp. 66 sqq. In the Monadology, Leibniz's position is the same as in the earlier of the passages quoted. 55 The definition of an idea is, for Leibniz, the statement of the elements which a complete analysis reveals in it. Cf. Meditationes de Cogmtione, Veritate et Inez's (1684) (E. 79 b ; G. iv. 423). 'When everything which is an element in a distinct idea, is in its turn distinctly known, or when analysis has been completely made, knowledge is adequate. I know not whether human knowledge can supply a perfect instance of this : the knowledge of numbers, however, approaches it.' 56 Leibniz uses the word enondation for enunciatio, which is the usual Latin translation of Aristotle's airu^iavoLs, or ^670? dntxpavTiicus. 57 Truths of reasoning have their sufficient reason in the self- evident, identical truths to which they may be reduced by analysis. Truths of fact can find a sufficient reason only in God. 18 Cf. Lotze, Microcosmus, bk. iii. ch. 5, § i (Eng. Tr., i. 372). Leibniz says * infinite division' instead of 'infinite divisibility,'' because bodies are infinitely divisible only as phenomena benefundatu and not as real beings. A real thing or substance must be indi- 238 THE MONADOLOGY of present and past forms and motions which go to make up the efficient cause of my present writing ; and there is an infinity of minute tendencies and dispositions of my soul, which go to make its final cause 59. 37. And as all this detail again involves other prior or more detailed contingent things, each of which still needs a similar analysis to yield its reason, we are no further forward : and the sufficient or final reason must be out- side of the sequence or series of particular contingent things, however infinite this series may be60. /3§y Thus the final reason of things must be in a neces- sary substance, in which the variety of particular changes exists only eminently R1, as in its source ; and this sub- stance we call God. (Theod. 7.) visible : it cannot consist of paries extra partes. And the ' infinite division ' of bodies is merely another way of describing the in- finite number of particular substances or Monads. 59 See Introduction, Part iii. p. 107. Cf. § 61. Here, in another form, arises the difficulty as to the relation of Leibniz's 'principles ' to one another. Apparently the efficient and the final cause combined make up the sufficient reason, neither by itself being enough. Yet elsewhere Leibniz represents efficient causes as ultimately depending on final causes. And efficient causes are by Leibniz usually identified with mechanical causes, whose principle is that of contradiction. See also Appendix F, p. 272. 50 This is an argument on the same lines as that by means of which Aristotle infers a ' prime mover.' It depends on his prin- ciple, dvajKrj arrival, i. e. we must come to a stop somewhere in the regress of causes or conditions. Cf. Phys. S, 6, 237b 3 ; 0, i, 251* 17 ; 0, 5, 256" 13. Also Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, Transcendental Dialectic, bk. ii. ch. 2 and 3. 61 Eminently in contrast with formally. The terms are Scholastic and they were adopted by Descartes. Thomas Aquinas expresses the difference thus : ' Whatever perfection is in the effect must also appear in the cause, after the same manner if the agent and the effect are of the same kind (univocaT) (thus man begets man), or in a more eminent, that is to say excellent, way, if the agent is of another kind (equivocal).' Descartes says : * By the objective reality of an idea, I mean the entity or being of the thing represented by the idea, in so far as this entity is in the idea ; and in the same way we may speak of an objective perfection or an objective design, &c. For all that we conceive as being in the objects of ideas is objectively THE MONADOLOGY 239 39. Now as this substance is a sufficient reason of all this variety of particulars, which are also connected together throughout ; there is only one God, and this God is sufficient™. 40. We may also hold that this supreme substance, which is unique, universal c:j and necessary, nothing out- er by representation in the ideas themselves. The same things are said to be formally in the objects of the ideas, when they exist in the objects just as we conceive them to exist ; and they are said to be eminently in the objects, when they do not really exist as we conceive them, but when they are so great that their excellence makes up . for this defect.' Reponses aux Deuxiemes Objections. Raisons qui prouvent I' existence de Dieu, iii. and iv., cf. note on this distinction in Veitch's Translation of Descartes. 'Formally' as opposed to 'objectively' is almost equivalent to our ' objectively' (as opposed to 1 subjectively ') or ' really ' (as opposed to ' in idea '). As opposed to eminently, formally is secundum eandem formam et rationem, while eminently is gradu or modo eminentiori. 62 That is to say, all particular things are connected together in one system, which implies one principle, one necessary substance, one God. The argument is not merely from the existence of order in the world to the existence of an intelligence which produces this order, but from the fact that the whole forms one system to the existence of one ultimate sufficient reason of the whole. Otherwise there might be various ' orders ' or ' disorders ' in conflict with one another, each pre-supposing its own first principle or ' God/ This is Leibniz's form of the Cosmological proof of the existence of God. 63 l Universal ' in the sense of being equally the cause or first principle of all things. The whole spirit of Leibniz's philosophy is opposed to the supposition of a universal substance or spirit, of which all particular substances are merely modes. Thus in the Considerations sur la Doctrine d'un Esprit Universel (1702) he endeavours to refute the view that ' there is but one spirit, which is universal and which animates the whole universe and all its parts, each according to its structure and according to the organs it possesses, as the same blast of wind produces a variety of sounds from different organ-pipes ' or that ' the universal spirit is like an ocean composed of an infinite number of drops, which are separated from it when they animate some particular organic body and which are reunited with their ocean after the destruction of the organism.' This is 'the view of Spinoza and of other similar authors, who will have it that there is only one substance, viz. God, who thinks, believes and wills one thing in me, and who thinks, believes and wills quite the opposite in some one else — an opinion the absurdity 240 THE MONADOLOGY side of it being independent of it, — this substance, which is a pure sequence of possible being, must be illimitable and must contain as much reality as is possible 64. \iy Whence it follows that God is absolutely perfect ; for perfection is nothing but amount of positive reality, in the strict sense, leaving out of account the limits or bounds in things which are limited. And where there are no bounds, that is to say in God, perfection is abso- lutely infinite. (Theod. 22, Pref. [E. 469 a; G. vi. 27].) /4?. It follows also that created beings derive their perfections from the influence of God, but that their imperfections come from their own nature, which is incapable of being without limits. For it is in this that they differ from God65. An instance of this original imperfection of created beings may be seen in the natural imrtia of bodies 66. (Theod. 20, 27-30, 153, 167, 377 sqq.) of which M. Bayle has well shown in several places in his dictionary' (E. 178 a, 181 b, 182 a ; G. vi. 529, 535, 537). 64 As God is the sufficient reason of all, nothing is independent of Him. But if His possibility were in any way limited, it must be by some possibility outside and independent of Him. Con- sequently His possibility cannot be limited. And unlimited possi- bility means unlimited reality and unlimited existence. For that which is possible must be real, unless there is something else with which it is not compossible, that is to say, unless there is some other possible thing, whose nature limits it. Cf. § 54 and Introduction, Part ii. p. 63. The argument in this and the following sections will become clear if we keep in view the idea which Leibniz seeks constantly to emphasize in every department of thought, namely that possibility or potentiality is never a mere empty capacity, a tabula rasa, a potentia nuda, but always, in however small a degree, a tendency to realization, which is kept back only by other similar tendencies. This is what is meant by the 'claims' and 'aspirations' of the Monads, mentioned in §§ 51 and 54. 65 Created beings must be essentially limited ; otherwise they would not be created, but would be identical with God. In the Theodice'e Leibniz (following the Scholastic principle, ton-urn habet causam efficientem, malum autem deficientem), uses this as a hypothesis by which to remove from God the responsibility for the existence of evil. The origin of evil is the essential imperfection of created substances ; and God is the cause only of the perfection or positive reality of created things. 66 This sentence is not given by E. It seems to have been added THE MONADOLOGY 24! 43. It is farther true that in God there is not only the source of existences but also that of essences, in so far as they are real, that is to say, the source of what is real in the possible67. For the understanding of God is the region of eternal truths or of the ideas on which they depend 68, and without Him there would be nothing real in the possibilities of things, and not only would there be nothing in existence, but nothing would even be possible. (Theod. 20.) by Leibniz in revising the first copy of the Monadology. G. gives it in a foot-note. The natural inertia of a body is its passivity or that in it which limits its activity. So far as the passivity of the body is real (i.e. not a mere appearance to us), it consists of confused perception. But God is adits purus, entirely without passivity, and His perceptions are all perfectly clear and distinct. 67 That is to say, God is not only the source of all actual existence, but also the source of all potential existence, of all that tends to exist. 'What is real in the possible ' is its tendency to exist. In a sense, 'essences' or 'possible' things are independent of God. He does not create them as essences. They are the objects of His understanding, and ' He is not the author of His own under- standing' (Theodicee, §380; E. 614 b ; G. vi. 341^ The nature _of essences or^possibiljties is determined solely by thejgrinciple ^)f contradiction. And yet, in another sense, they may be said to be dependent upon God, Inasmuch as they are all expressions of His nature in one or another aspect or with particular limitations. His freedom, however, extends only to a choice of those which shall actually exist, and this choice is determined by His wisdom and His goodness, having regard to the nature of the ' essences ' themselves. 'Without Him there would be nothing in existence,' for the existence of things is the result of His will, His choice. 'Without Him nothing would be possible' for all that is possible is the object of His understanding, and as His understanding is perfect (i.e. entirely free from confusion in its perceptions), its object must be the ultimate nature of things, that is, the very essence of God Himself. Thus in § 44 Leibniz practically identifies 'essences' or 'possibilities' with 'eternal truths.' Cf. Introduction, Part ii. p. 66. 68 Leibniz connects this part of his system with Plato's world of ideas. He mentions as one of the ' many most excellent doctrines of Plato' that 'there is in the Divine mind an intelligible world, which I also am wont to call the region of ideas.' Epistola ad Hanschium (1707% E. 445 b. R 242 THE MONADOLOGY 44. For 69 if there is a reality in essences or possibilities, or rather in eternal truths, this reality must needs be founded in something existing and actual, and conse- quently in the existence of the necessary Being, in whom essence involves existence, or in whom to be possible is to be actual70. (Theod. "184-189, 335.) 45. Thus God alone (or the necessary Being) has this prerogative that He must necessarily exist, if He is pos- sible. And as nothing can interfere 'with the possibility of that which involves no limits, no negation and conse- quently no contradiction, this [His possibility] is sufficient of itself to make known the existence of God a priori We have thus proved it, through the reality of eternal truths. But a little while ago 71 we proved it also a poste- riori, since there exist contingent beings, which can have their final or sufficient reason only in the necessary Being, which has the reason of its existence in itself. 46. We must not, however, imagine, as some do, that eternal truths, being dependent on God, are arbitraiy and depend on His will, as Descartes 72, and afterwards 69 G. reads car, E. cependant. 70 See Appendix G, p. 274. 7l §§ 36-39- 72 Cf. Descartes, Lettre au Pere Mersenne (Cousin's ed., vol. vi. p. 109). * The metaphysical truths which you call eternal have been established by God and are entirely dependent upon Him, like all other created things. Indeed, to say that these truths are independent of God is to speak of God as a Jupiter or a Saturn and to subject Him to Styx and the Fates. . . . God has established these laws in nature, just as a king establishes laws in his kingdom.' Cf. loc. cit., p. 103. ' We cannot without blasphemy say that the truth of anything precedes the knowledge which God has of it, for in God willing and knowing are one.' Elsewhere he says that God was perfectly free to make it untrue that the three angles of a triangle should be equal to two right-angles. As early as 1671. in a letter to Honoratus Fabri, Leibniz writes : ' If truths and the natures of things are dependent on the choice of God, I do not see how knowledge [scientia] or even will can be attributed to Him. For will certainly presupposes some understanding, since no one can will except in view of some good [sub ratione from']. But under- standing presupposes something that can be understood, that is to say, some nature. But if all natures are the result of will. THE MONADOLOGY 243 M. Poiret73, appear to have held. That is true only of contingent truths, of which the principle is fitness [con- venance] 74 or choice of the best, whereas necessary truths ; depend solely on His understanding and are its inner object. (Theod. 180-184, 185, 335, 351, 380.) 47. Thus God alone is the primary unity or original simple substance, of which all created or derivative Monads are products and have their birth, so to speak, through continual fulgurations 75 of the Divinity from understanding also will be the result of will. How, then, does will presuppose understanding?' (G. iv. 259). The point was much discussed by the Scholastics, with special reference to the question whether or not the moral law is independent of the will of God. Descartes's view is in harmony with that of Duns Scotus, while Leibniz follows Thomas Aquinas. For Descartes, the Divine and the human understanding differ in kind : for Leibniz they differ merely in degree. 73 Pierre Poiret (1646-1719), a Calvinist minister, who held a charge in the Duchy of Zweibriicken, in the Ehine Palatinate. He was at first a Cartesian and published a book, Cogitatioms rationales de Deo, Anima et Malo, which Bayle attacked. Afterwards he came under the influence of Antoinette Bourignon, the Dutch religious enthusiast, whose life he wrote and whose views he expounded at very great length. This influence led him to attack Cartesianism with much fervour, and he is now remembered as a mystic rather than as a philosopher. 74 By convenance is meant mutual conformity, of such a kind that things ' fit into ' one another in the most perfect way. Thus the principle of convenance or of the best is what we should now call the idea of system. With Leibniz it is the same as the principle of sufficient reason, which is the principle of conditioned, as distinct from unconditional reality or truth. Cf. note 85. '5 That is to say, ' flashings ' or 'sudden emanations/ ' God is the primary centre from which all else emanates' (G. iv. 553). Cf. the Stoic rovos which Cleanthes calls a ' stroke of fire ' (71X7777) -nvpos\ Frag. 76. The relation of God to the other Monads is the crux of Leibniz's philosophy. He wishes to maintain both the individuality of the Monads and their essential unity with God. Thus he seems to take fulguration as a middle term between creation and emana- tion. ' Creation ' would mean too complete a severance between God and the other Monads ; ' emanation ' would mean too complete an identity between them. ' Fulguration ' means that the Monad is not absolutely created out of nothing nor, on the other hand, merely a mode or an absolutely necessary product of the Divine K 2 244 THE MONADOLOGY moment to moment, limited by the receptivity of the created being, of whose essence it is to have limits. (Theod. 382-391, 398, 395.) 48. In God there is Power, which is the source of all, also Knoivledge, whose content is the variety of the ideas, and nnally Will, which makes changes or products according to the principle of the best76. (Theod. 7, 149, nature, but that it is a possibility tending to realize itself, yet requiring the assistance, choice or will of God to set it free from the counteracting influence of opposite possibilities. As a possibility it has essential limits (i. e. it is not entirely perfect, actus purus) ; but it is ready to spring or ' flash ' into being, at the will of God. If there were no choice of God, possibilities would simply counteract one another. But His choice means no more than the removal of hindrances to development, in the case of certain 'elect* possi- bilities. Creation adds no new being to the universe, and yet it is not emanation, in the sense of a mere modification of the one Eternal Being. Thus the ' continual fulgurations ' of Leibniz are to be distinguished from the ' continual creation ' of Descartes. According to Leibniz, conservation is not, as with Descartes, a miraculous renewal of the existence of things from moment to moment, an absolute re-creation constantly repeated ; but it is the continuance of the activity, choice or .will of God, by which certain possible things were set free to exist and through which alone they can persist. The successive states of any being are neither completely independent of one another, so that at each moment there is a new creation (Descartes), nor are they so absolutely dependent on one another that each proceeds from its predecessor by a logical or mathematical necessity (Spinoza), but they are connected together in a sequence which has its ground in the nature of the being, so that each is automatically unfolded from its predecessor according to a regular law, provided that God chooses to allow this unfolding. The * continual fulgurations ' are the continual exercise of God's will in allowing the Monads of the actual world to unfold or develop their nature. Cf. On the ultimate Origination of Things, p. 344. 76 In the Theodicee (§ 150 ; E. 549 a ; G. vi. 199) Leibniz hints at a connexion between this characterization of God's nature and the doctrine of the Trinity. ' Some have even thought that there is in these three perfections of God a hidden reference to the Holy Trinity : that power has reference to the Father, that is to say, to the Godhead [Divinite] ; wisdom to the eternal Word, which is called Ao-yos by the most sublime of the evangelists ; and will or love to the Holy Spirit.' THE MONADOLOGY 245 150.) These characteristics correspond to what in the created Monads forms the ground or basis 77, to the faculty of Perception and to the faculty of Appetition. But in God these attributes are absolutely infinite or perfect ; and in the created Monads or the Entelechies (or perfectihabiae, as Hermolaus Barbarus translated the word 78) there are . only imitations of these attributes, according to the degree of perfection of the Monad. (Theod. "87.) 49. A created thing is said to act outwardly 79 in so far I as it has perfection, and to suffer [or be passive, pdtir] in relation to another, in so far as it is imperfect. Thus activity [action] is attributed to a Monad, in so far as it has distinct perceptions, and passivity [passion] in so far as its perceptions are confused. (Theod. 32, 66, 386.) 50. And one created thing is more perfect than another, in this, that there is found in the more perfect that which serves to explain a priori what takes place in the less perfect, and it is on this account that the former is said to act upon the latter 80. 77 Leibniz does not elsewhere discriminate three elements in the created Monad, and we must not suppose that the 'ground or basis' is anything in itself, apart from the two 'faculties.' Leibniz wishes to emphasize the view that the Monad, whether created or uncreated, is essentially force or activity, manifesting itself -in perception and appetition. 78 perfectihabia (from perfecte and habeo} was formed to correspond to evT(\fxfta (from cfrcAcDs and exftv)' Cf. note 32. Hermolaus Barbarus or Ermolao Barbaro (1454-1493) was an Italian scholar who endeavoured, by means of translations of Aristotle and of the Aristotelian commentaries of Themistius, to make known the true Aristotelian doctrine as against the degenerate forms which Scholasticism had given it. He came of a Venetian family and was Professor of Philosophy at Padua, where he lectured on Aristotle's Ethics. 79 Of course, no Monad really does act outside itself. This is merely Leibniz's explanation of what we mean when we speak of outward action, just as the Copernican system explains what we mean when we speak of ' sunrise ' and { sunset/ though the sun neither ' rises ' nor ' sets.' 80 Thus the explanation or reason of an event is its actual cause. This connects itself with Leibniz's view that the existence of 246 THE MONADOLOGY 51. But in simple substances the influence of one Monad upon another is only ideal, and it can have its effect only through the mediation of God, in _so_far_as in the ideas of God any Monad rightly claims that God, in regulating the others from the beginning of things, should have regard to it. For since one created Monad cannot have any physical influence upon the inner being of another, it is only by this means that the one can be dependent upon the other 81. (Theod. 9, 54, 65, 66, 201. Abrege. Object. 3.^ 52. Accordingly, among created things, activities and passivities are mutual. For God, comparing two simple substances, finds in each reasons which oblige Him to adapt the other to it 82, and consequently what is active in certain respects is passive from another point of view 83 ; a thing arises solely from the liberating of its essential activities, and that the Monads claim existence in proportion to their per- fection, that is to say, to the distinctness of their perceptions. Cause and effect are relative : every created Monad is both at once. God alone is pure cause or reason (actus purus). Cause = relative activity = relative distinctness of perception. This may instructively be compared and contrasted with the views of Berkeley and Hume regarding cause and 'necessary connexion.' See Introduction. Part iii. p. 105. Cf. also Spinoza, Ethics, Part iii. Def. i and 2, and Prop, i, 2 and 3. 81 We have here the principle of the Pre-established Harmony (further referred to in §§ 80 and 81). It is a harmony or mutual compatibility in the very nature of things, anterior to their creation. Its perfection in the actual world is the ground of God's choice of that world ; and thus it is not in any sense a created harmony. In this respect it differs from every form of Occa- sionalism. See Introduction, Part ii. pp. 39 sqq. 82 No two simple substances are exactly the same, yet all represent the same universe. Therefore a perception which is comparatively distinct in one must be comparatively confused in another or others, and whatever changes take place in one must be accom- panied by corresponding changes in the others. Thus each fits into the others. 63 Leibniz's expression here is point de consideration. But he generally uses the phrase point de vue, which he introduced as a regular term in philosophical literature. It need hardly be remarked that the term has a peculiar importance in Leibniz's philosophy. THE MONADOLOGY 247 active in so far as what we distinctly know in it serves to explain [rendre raison de] what takes place in another, and passive in so far as the explanation [raison] of what takes place in it is to be found in that which is distinctly known in another. (Theod. 66.) 53. Now, as in the Ideas of God there is an infinite number of possible universes, and as only one of them can be actual, there must be a sufficient reason for the choice of God, which leads Him to decide upon one rather • than another84. (Theod. 8, 10, 44, 173, 196 sqq., 225, 414-416.) 54. And this reason can be found only in the fitness [convenance], or in the degrees of perfection, that these worlds possess 85, since each possible thing has the right to aspire to existence in proportion to the amount of per- fection rTWlfckainsW germ86. (Theod. 74, 167, 350, 201, 130, 352, 345 »qq., 354.) 84 See Introduction, Part ii. p. 65. 85 See Monadology, note 74. God is not compelled by an absolute, metaphysical necessity, but ' inclined ' by a moral necessity to create the world which, as one harmonious system, is the best. The distinction between moral necessity and absolute compulsion is of Scholastic origin. ' Possible things are those which do not involve a contradiction. Actual things are nothing but the possible things which, all things considered, are the best. Therefore things which are less perfect are not on that account impossible ; for we must distinguish between the things which God can do and those He wills to do. He can do everything, He wills to do the best.' Epistola ad Bernoullium (1699), (G. Math. iii. 574). 86 This aspiration to existence is the tendency to pass into existence and to proceed from confused to distinct perceptions, which makes the 'possible* things of Leibniz real essences as distinct from purely indeterminate capacities. Possibilities, accord- ing to Leibniz, are never quite empty : they are always realities in germ. Of. notes 64 and 67. ' From the very fact that there exists something rather than nothing, we must recognize that in possible things, or in possibility or essence itself, there is a certain need of existence [exigentiam existentiae] or (so to speak) a certain aspiration to exist, and, in a word, that essence by itself tends to existence. Whence it further follows that all possible things, i. e. things expressing essence or possible reality, tend with equal right to existence in proportion to the quantity of essence or reality they 248 THE MONADOLOGY 55. Thus the actual existence of the best that wisdom makes known to God is due to this, that His goodness makes Him choose it, and His power makes Him produce it87. (Theod. 8, 78, 80, 84, 119, 204, 206, 208. Abregt. Object, i and 8.) 56. Now this connexion or adaptation of all created things to each and of each to all, means that each simple substance has relations which express all the others, and, consequently, that it is a perpetual living mirror of the universe88. (Theod. 130, 360.) 57. And as the same town, looked at from various sides, appears quite different and becomes as it were numerous in aspects [perspectivement] ; even so, as a result of the infinite number of simple substances, it is as if there were so many different universes, which, nevertheless are nothing but aspects [perspectives] of a single universe, according to the special point of view of each Monad 89. (Theod. 147.) . contain or to their degree of perfection ; for perfection is nothing but quantity of essence.' Ultimate Origination of Things, p. 340. 87 This section states briefly the principles of Leibniz's Optimism, •which are fully expounded and defended in the Theodicee. A world entirely free from evil would be indistinguishable from God Himself. The evil of the world arises entirely from the essential limitations of created things — their limitations as essences or possibilities. Consequently evil is not created by God ; but He creates the universe in which there is the least amount of evil that is possible in any system of things. 88 Cf. Nicholas of Cusa, Dialogi de ludo gloli (1454-59% i- J57 a : ' The whole is reflected in all the parts ; all things keep their own relation [habitudo] and proportion to the universe.' Also De docta ignorantia (1440), i. n : ' Visible things are images of the invisible, and the Creator can be seen and known by the creatures as in a mirror darkly [quasi in speculo et aenigmate].' 89 The ' point of view ' of each Monad is its body. But we must not give a spatial meaning to the expression, as if the Monad's point of view depended on its having this or that position in space. For the Monad is absolutely non-spatial, and the nature of its body depends on the degree of confusedness (or distinctness) of its perceptions. Thus to say that the body is the point of view of the soul means simply that the particular way in which the soul represents or perceives the universe is determined by the degree THE MONADOLOGY 249 58. And by this means there is obtained as great variety as possible, along with the greatest possible order ; that is to say, it is the way to get as much perfection as possible90. (TJieod. 120, 124, 241 sqq., 214, 243, 275.) 59. Besides, no hypothesis but this (which I venture to call proved) fittingly exalts the greatness of God ; and this Monsieur Bayle recognized when, in his Dictionary (article Eorarius*1}, he raised objections to it, in which of distinctness of its perceptions. Cf. Theodicee, § 357 (E. 607 b ; G. vi. 327). ' The projections of perspective, which, in the case of the circle, are the same as the Conic Sections, show that one and the same circle can be represented by an ellipse, by a parabola and by a hyperbola, and even by another circle, by a straight line and by a point. Nothing seems more different, nothing more unlike, than these figures ; and yet there is an exact relation between them, point for point. Thus it must be recognized that each soul represents to itself the universe, according to its point of view and by a relation peculiar to itself; but in this there always continues to be a perfect harmony.' 90 For Leibniz the highest perfection is the most complete unity or order in the greatest variety. The Monads have the most complete unity, because the essence of each consists in representing the same universe, while they have the greatest variety, because the points of view from which they represent it are infinitely various. ' For a world to be possible, it is enough that it should have intelligibility ; but in order to exist it must have a pre- eminence [prevalence] in intelligibility or order ; for there is order in proportion as there is much to distinguish in a manifold [multitude].' Lettre a Bourguet (1712 ?) (E. 718 b ; G. iii. 558). 91 See note 29. Bayle compares Leibniz's theory to the sup- position that a ship might be constructed of such a kind that entirely by itself, without captain or crew, it could sail from place to place for years on end, accommodating itself to varying winds, avoiding shoals, casting and weighing anchor, seeking a haven when necessary and doing all that a normal ship can. He admits that the omnipotence of God could give such a power to a ship, biit he maintains that the nature of the ship would make it impossible for it to receive such a power. And ' however infinite be the knowledge and power of God, He cannot, by means of a machine which lacks a certain part, do that which requires the help of that part.' Thus Bayle argues against the possibility of complete spontaneity in the Monads, and consequently maintains that the Deus ex machina is involved in Leibniz's Pre-established Harmony quite as much as in Occasionalism. 250 THE MONADOLOGY indeed he was inclined to think that I was attributing too much to God— more than it is possible to attribute. But he was unable to give any reason which could show the impossibility of this universal harmony, according to which every substance exactly expresses all others through the relations it has with them. 60. Further, in what I have just said there may be seen the reasons a priori why things could not be other- wise than they are. For God in regulating the whole has had regard 92 to each part, and in particular to each Monad, whose nature being to represent, nothing can confine it to the representing of only one part of things ; though it is true that this representation is merely confused as regards the variety of particular things \le detail] in the whole universe, and can be distinct only as regards a small part of things, namely, those which are either nearest or greatest93 in relation to each of the Monads; otherwise each Monad would be a deity. It is not as regards their object, but as regards the different ways in which they have knowledge of their object, that the Monads are limited 94. In a confused way they all strive after [vont a] the infinite, the whole 95 ; but they are limited and differentiated through the degrees of their distinct perceptions. 6 1. And compounds are in this respect analogous with 92 So G. E. reads ' has a regard ' [a un egard]. >3 If the Monads are non-spatial, how can we speak of anything being nearest or greatest in relation to a Monad ? Every Monad has a body of some kind and this body is confusedly perceived as spatial in itself and in relation to other bodies, though really it is nothing but an aggregate of non-spatial Monads. When therefore it is said that certain things are near or great in relation to a Monad, what is meant is that they are near or great in relation to the body of the Monad. 94 That is to say, thought in the widest sense, conscious or un- conscious, is limited only by itself : there can be nothing that is not an object of thought, more or less adequate. Contrast with this the position of Kant. See Introduction, Part iv, pp. 178 sqq. 95 Cf. Nicholas of Cusa, Dialogus de Genesi (1447) 72 b : 'All things seek the same, which is something absolute.' THE MONADOLOGY 251 [symbolisent avec %] simple substances. For all is a plenum (and thus all matter is connected together) and in the plenum every motion has an effect upon distant bodies in proportion to their distance, so that each body not only is affected by those which are in contact with it and in some way feels the effect of eveiything that happens to them, but also is mediately affected by bodies adjoining those with which it itself is in immediate contact. Wherefore it follows that this inter-communication of things extends to any distance, however great. And consequently every body feels the effect of all that takes place in the uni- verse, so that he who sees all might read in each what is happening everywhere, and even what has happened or shall happen, observing in the present that which is far off as well in time as in place : o-v/zTrvoca Travra, as Hippocrates said 97. But a soul can read in itself only 9(5 The expression ' symbolize ' suggests the ' calculus ' idea which' is so continually in Leibniz's mind. As numbers are symbols of the things numbered, and we make accurate calculations without referring at every step to the particular things for which our symbols stand, so in general unanalyzed thoughts may be symbols of their simple elements. In the same way compound things are symbols of the simple substances which compose them. What is perceived confusedly in compounds is not a mere illusion but an imperfect representation or symbol of the real characteristics of simple substances. Thus, in this section, Leibniz would say that the spatial or material plenum (which is a confused perception of ours) is a symbol of the infinite (or perfectly complete) series of Monads, which has no gaps, since the Monads differ from one another by infinitely small degrees. Similarly, the material action and re-action throughout the universe, such that a change at any one point affects every other, is a symbol of the Pre-established Harmony among the Monads. And, again, the fact that every- thing that happens, has happened or shall happen in the universe might be read in any one body is a symbol of the representative character of each Monad as ideally containing the whole within itself. It is because they are thus symbolic that the phenomena of the material world are phenomena benefundata. 97 'Svpirvota (the noun) is probably a corruption from ovpirvoa (the adjective), ' in agreement,' lit. ' breathing together/ conspirantia. Leibniz makes the same quotation in the New Essays, Introduction, p. 373. He there translates the phrase by the words 'tout est 252 THE MONADOLOGY that which is there represented distinctly ; it cannot all at once unroll everything that is enfolded in it98, for its complexity is infinite". The mistake may be due to an imperfect recollection of the phrase in Hippocrates : £vppoia /Ja, ^v^irvoia juia, £vp.TraOta iravra. (De Alimento, 4, Littre, (Euvres d'Hippocrate, vol. ix. p. 106). Cf. Plutarch, De fato, 574 E : TO va(t oioineiaOat rovftf rov nuapov avfiirvovv, Kal avfjuraBfj, avrbv avrw ovra, For a later statement of the same position, see Fichte, Werke, ii. 178 sqq. 'In every moment of her duration, nature is one connected whole : in every moment each part must be what it is, because all the others are what they are. . . . You cannot conceive even the position of a grain of sand other than it is in the present without being compelled to conceive the whole indefinite past as having been other than it has been, and the whole indefinite future other than it will be. ... I am what I am because in this conjuncture of the great whole of nature only such, and no other, was possible ; and a spirit who could look through the secrets of nature would, from knowing one single man, be able distinctly to declare what men had formerly existed and what men would exist at any future moment ; in one individual he would cognize all real individuals. My connexion, then, with the whole of nature is that which determines what I have been, am, and shall be, and the same spirit would be able, from any possible moment of my existence, to discover infallibly what I had been and what I was to become.' [Trans, by Prof. Adamson, Philosophy of Kant ', p. 221.] 98 E. reads ses regies: G. reads sesreplis. The latter phrase is used in the Principles of Nature and of Grace, § 13. y9 Cf. Leibnitiana, Dutens, vol. vi. Part i. p. 332. ' I admit that after death we do not at first remember what we were, for this is neither naturally right nor in accordance with the fitness of things [ni propre ni bienseant dans la nature]. Nevertheless I believe that whatever has once happened to the soul is eternally imprinted upon it, although it does not at all times come back to us in memory ; just as we know a number of things which we do not always recollect, unless something suggests them and makes us think aboxit them. For who can remember all things ? But since in nature nothing is futile and nothing is lost, but everything tends to perfection and maturity, each image our soul receives will ultimately become one [un tout] with the things which are to come, so that we shall be able to see all as in a mirror and thence to derive that which we shall find to be more fitted to satisfy us. Whence it follows that the more virtuous we have been and the more good deeds we have done, the more shall we have of joy and satisfaction.' • , ^^L^^ . THE MONADOLOGY 253 62. Thus, although each created Monad represents the whole universe, it represents more distinctly the body which specially pertains to it, and of which it is the entelechy100;land as this body expresses the whole uni- verse through the connexion of all matter in the plenum, j[ the soul also represents the whole universe in representing this body, which belongs to it in a special way. (Theod. 400.) 63. The body belonging to a Monad (which is its entelechy or its soul) constitutes along with the ente- lechy what may be called a living being, and along with the soul what is called an animal 10LH Now this body of a living being or of an animal is always organic ; for, as every Monad is, in its own way, a mirror of the universe, and as the universe is ruled according to a perfect order, ' there must also be order in that which represents it, i. e. in the perceptions of the soul, and consequently there must be order in the body, through which the universe is represented in the soul 102. ^(Theod. 403.) 100 See note 32. The entelechy or soul is at once the final cause of the body and the power which controls it or the force which acts through it. As dominant Monad, the soul has more clearly the perceptions which are relatively confused in the Monads implied by the body. The soul is thus relatively the perfection of the body. And similarly, in the soul is to be read the reason (i. e. the distinct perception) of what takes place in the body, and it is therefore the activity or force of the body. Cf. Introduction, Part iii. p. no. 101 See § 19. Leibniz uses the term living being not as including all beings which have life, but specifically with reference only to those whose dominant Monad is unconscious, while in the animal (as distinct from the living 'being') the dominant Monad has con- sciousness and memory. 102 Thus order and organism are conceived by Leibniz under the idea of an infinite series of elements, each differing from its neighbour to an infinitely small extent. The Monad-series of the universe, extending from God to the lowest of Monads, is reflected in the structure of the individual organism, extending from the dominant Monad downwards, and that again is reflected in the series of perceptions within each Monad itself, extending from the most distinct perceptions to which it has attained down to the most obscure. 254 THE MONADOLOGY 64. Thus the organic body of each living being is a kind of divine machine or natural automaton, which infinitely surpasses all artificial automata. For a machine made by the skill of man is not a machine103 in each of its parts. For instance, the tooth of a brass wheel has parts or fragments which for us are not artificial products, and which do not have the special characteristics of the machine, for they give no indication of the use for which the wheel was intended. But the machines of nature, namely, living bodies, are still machines in their smallest parts ad infinitum 10*. It is this that constitutes the dif- 103 i. e. not a machine made by man. From another point of view, as a product of nature, it is (as this section says) a machine in its smallest parts, for in reality all bodies are living bodies. Thus the words ' for us ' in the next sentence of this section were added by Leibniz in a revision of his original manuscript, evidently in order to suggest that while the fragments of the wheel are not products of ' human art,' they are yet products of ' divine art.' 104 Cf. Lettre a M. Vfctiqw de Meaiix (Bossuet) (1692), (Foucher de Careil, i. 277 ; Dutens, i. 531). ' The machines of nature are machines throughout, however small a part of them we take ; or rather the least part is itself an infinite world, which even expresses in its own way all that there is in the rest of the universe. That passes our imagination, yet we know that it must be so ; and all that infinitely infinite variety is animated in all its parts by a constructive [architectonique] wisdom that is more than infinite. It may be said that there is Harmony, Geometry, Meta- physics, and, so to speak, Ethics [morale] everywhere, and (what is surprising) in one sense each substance acts spontaneously as independent of all other created things, while in another sense, all others compel it to adapt itself to them ; so that it may be said that all nature is full of miracles, but miracles of reason, miracles which become miracles in virtue of their being rational, in a way which amazes us. For the reasons of things follow one another in an infinite succession [s't/ pousse a un progres infini\ so that our mind while it sees that things must be so, cannot follow so as to comprehend. Formerly people admired nature without in any way understanding it, and that was supposed to be the right thing to do. Latterly they have begun to think nature so easy to understand that they have developed a contempt for it, and some of the new philosophers even encourage themselves in idleness by imagining that they know enough about nature already.' See also Introduction, Part iii. p. 108. THE MONADOLOGY 255 ference between nature and art, that is to say, between the divine art and ours 105. (Theod. 134, 146, 194, 403.) 65. And the Author of nature has been able to employ this divine and infinitely wonderful power of art, because each portion of matter is not only infinitely divisible, as the ancients observed 106, but is also actually subdivided without end 107, each part into further parts, of which 103 Cf. Nicholas of Cusa, Idiotae Libri quatuor, iii. 2, 82 a. 'Humanae artes imagines Divinae arils' 106 See Aristotle, Phys., Z, 9, 23gb 5. Ov yap avyKfirai 6 xpovos (tc TU>V vvv a.8iaip(TQJv, uancp ov8' d\Xo yw€-y60o? ovSev. Cf. Phys., Z, I, 23 ib 18 ; Z, 4 (TO Se neral3a\\ov airav avayfcr) Siaipcrov fivai) ; De Caelo, T, I, 298b 33. See also Bayle's Dictionary, article ' Zeno,' notes F and G. 107 Cf. Reponse a la Uttre de M. Foucher (1693), (E. 118 b. ; G. i. 416). ' There is no part of matter which is not, I do not say divisible, but actually divided ; and consequently the smallest particle must be considered as a world filled with an infinity of different creatures.' The paradox in such statements as these arises from the way in which Leibniz speaks of matter as composed of non-spatial elements. Leibniz regards matter as a mere aggregate and as therefore not itself a real substance. But he never explains what he means by an aggregate of Monads, each of which is non- quantitative. Again it may be asked whether a real whole can consist of an infinite number of real parts ? Does not infinite divisibility mean that it is impossible to bring to an end the enumeration of parts, because the relation of whole to parts is so indefinite that we have no means of determining what exactly is a part? Thus the -term 'infinite' here means that the process of division is one which can never be completed. Consequently it seems self-contradictory to speak of things as 'actually sub- divided without end' or infinitely. (Cf. Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, First and Second Antinomies. See also Bosanquet's Logic, vol. i. pp. 172 sqq.) It was Euler, the mathematician, who first brought this criticism against Leibniz, saying that the existence of units in the shape of Monads implies the finite divisibility of matter, while Leibniz at the same time maintains its infinite divisibility. (Lettres a une Princesse d'Allemagne (1761), Brewster's Trans , vol. ii. pp. 30 sqq.) Euler's argument is directed mainly against the Wolffian adaptation of Leibniz's position. Leibniz might reply that matter as infinitely divisible, is a mere pheno- menon, resulting from an actual infinity of real Monads. But even in this explanation the idea of ' infinite ' seems to be used in two opposite senses (i) as equivalent to 'incapable of completion," (2) as equivalent to ' absolutely complete.' 256 THE MONADOLOGY each has some motion of its own ; otherwise it would be impossible for each portion of matter to express the whole universe 108. (Theod. Prelim., Disc, de la Conform. 70, and 195.) 66. Whence it appears that in the smallest particle of matter there is a world of creatures, living beings, animals, entelechies, souls. 67. Each portion of matter may be conceived as like a garden full of plants and like a pond full of fishes. But each branch of every plant, each member of every animal, each drop of its liquid parts is also some such garden or pond. 68. And though the earth and the air which are between the plants of the garden, or the water which is between the fish of the pond, be neither plant nor fish ; yet they also contain plants and fishes, but mostly so minute as to be imperceptible to us 109. 108 rj^ « p0r{;ions Of matter,' of which Leibniz here speaks, are ultimately Monads, each of which must ideally contain the whole universe. The Monads are infinite in number, and each, as it ideally contains all, must therefore contain an infinity of ' parts.' Or the argument which Leibniz implies may be otherwise put thus : If the ' portions of matter ' are not actually subdivided without end, there must be ultimate undivided atoms. But such atoms necessarily imply a void ; they are inconsistent with a plenum. And unless there is a plenum it is impossible for each portion of matter to ' express ' or be aifected by all the rest. 109 Leibniz had a deep interest in the remarkable development of microscopic investigation, which took place during his lifetime. He frequently refers to the work of Leuwenhoek, the discoverer of spermatozoa, Swammerdam, the entomologist, and Malpighi, who, among many other works, made a microscopic study of the physio- logy of animals and plants. In a Meditation sur la notion commune de la Justice (Moll at, p. 66), Leibniz says : ' It is very necessary to advance our microscopical knowledge. Scarce ten men in the world are earnestly devoted to it ; and though there were a hundred thousand, they would not be too many for the discovery of the important wonders of this new world which is the inside of the world we know and which is capable of making our knowledge a hundred thousand times as extensive as it is. For this reason I have often wished that great princes might be led to make arrangements for this and to support people who would devote THE MONADOLOGY 257 69. Thus there is nothing fallow, nothing sterile, nothing dead in the universe, no chaos, no confusion save in appearance nia (St. James, iii. 15, 17). Leibniz seems himself to have intended to supply the want to which he here refers, for he sketched the outline of a book on the subject, which is printed by Mollat (pp. 8 sqq.), under the title Tabulae duae disciplinae juris naturae et gentium secundum disciplinam Christianorum. In this he refers to St. James as ' calling charity voftos paei\iK6s, the royal law (ch. ii. 8), inasmuch as it comes from the supreme King (St. Paul, Romans, i. 32, ducaiajjia rov foot)).' (Mollat, p. n.) 55 While admitting a right of this kind as distinct from natural right, Leibniz maintains that the two ought always to be in harmony. He thus condemns the view of Hobbes, that the basis of right is power, which he identifies with the view of Thrasymachus in Plato's Republic, bk. i. (see Mollat, p. 57 sqq.). Cf. Le Portrait du Prince (Klopp, iv. 461) : 'As the order of States is established on the authority of those who govern them and on the dependence of their peoples, nature which destines men for civil life endows them at birth with different qualities, some for commanding, others for obeying, in order that the power of the sovereign in a monarchy and the inequality between those who command and those who obey in a republic, be no less founded on nature than on law, on virtue than on fortune. So princes ought to be above their subjects by their virtue and their natural qualities, as they are above them by the authority which the laws give them, in 296 ON THE NOTIONS OF EIGHT AND JUSTICE outside of the commonwealth or among those who are sharers in supreme power (of whom there are sometimes several even in the same commonwealth) there is the sphere of the voluntary law of nations, accepted by the tacit consent of the peoples. . . . But Christians have also another common bond, namely the positive Divine law [jus] which is contained in the sacred books. To which are to be added the sacred canons received by the whole Church and afterwards in the West the Papal law [jures] to which kings and peoples submit themselves. And in general (and certainly not against reason) it seems for a long time to have been accepted, before the schism of last century, that there should be understood to be a certain general commonwealth of the Christian nations, the heads of which were in sacred things the Pope [Pontifex Maximus] and in temporal things the Emperor of the Romans, who also seemed to retain so much of the law of the old Roman monarchy as was needed for the common good of Christendom, without prejudice to the Right of kings and the liberty of princes. order to reign both by natural right and by civil right, like the first kings in the world, who having been raised to the government of their peoples by their virtue and their intellectual gifts, com- nianded as much by nature as by law, by merit as by fortune.' NEW SYSTEM OF THE NATURE OF SUB- STANCES AND OF THE COMMUNICATION1 BETWEEN THEM, AS WELL AS OF THE UNION THERE IS BETWEEN SOUL AND BODY2. 1695. PREFATORY NOTE. IN this paper, which appeared anonymously in the Journal des Savants of June, 1695, we nave Leibniz's first public state- ment of his New System (see Introduction, Part i. p. 12). In character it is much more tentative than his later writings, and it is only towards the end of the paper (§• 17) that he ventures to speak of his view as 'more than a hypothesis.' This is very characteristic of Leibniz : he likes to advance by suggestion and hypothesis. But he regards hypothesis as merely a stepping-stone : he will not rest there if it is possible to go farther. ' In matters where certainty can be obtained, I will not use hypotheses,' he says to Bernouilli (G. Math. iii. 575). And nearly twenty years after he published the New System, Leibniz writes of ' this hypothesis, which I venture to call proved ' (Monadology, § 59). Thus the peculiar interest of the New System is that it lets us see something of Leibniz's philosophy in the making. For in this work he writes histori- cally, indicating to us the course which his thought took. The New System may be divided into two main parts, in the first of which (§§ i-n inclusive) Leibniz shows us how he was 1 i. e. inter-relation or interaction. 3 The title in the First Draft is New system for explaining the nature of substances and their communication with one another, as well as the union of soul with body. 298 NEW SYSTEM led to re-introduce into philosophy the ' substantial forms ' of the Scholastics, and in what sense these forms, souls, simple substances or real units are to be understood ; while in the second (§§ 12-18) he applies his theory of substance to the question of the relation between soul and body, mind and matter, and finds that the problem can be satisfactorily solved only through the hypothesis of a pre-established harmony between all simple substances. Analyzing the title of the paper, we may say that the first part deals with the nature of substances and the second with their communication. Erdmann (E. 124 sqq.) gives the New System as it was origin- ally published. Gerhardt (G. iv. 477 sqq.) gives it as it was afterwards revised and altered by Leibniz, and he also prints an interesting First Draft of it. I have translated from Gerhardt's text, indicating its differences from Erdmann's; and in the notes will be found some passages from the First Draft. The paragraphs are numbered in E. ; but not in G. i. Several years ago I conceived this system and had communications about it with learned men, especially with one of the greatest theologians and philosophers of our time3, who, having been informed of some of my opinions by a person of the highest rank4, had found them very paradoxical5. But having received explana- tions from me, he withdrew what he had said in the 3 * Mons. Arnauld.' Note by Leibniz, who tells us also that with regard to his New System he ' followed the rule of Horace : nonumque prematur in annum ' (G. iv. 490). There is an interesting account of Arnauld and his friends in Stephen's Essays in Ecclesiastical Biography, vol. i, Essay vi, The Port-Eoyalists. * Landgraf Ernest of Hesse-Kheinfels (1623-1693), who in 1652, shortly after the close of the Thirty Years' War, became a Eoman Catholic and published a justification of the course he had taken. A copy of this work he sent to the Duke of Brunswick, and he thus came into communication with Leibniz. They kept up a correspondence on theological and ecclesiastical subjects until the death of the Landgraf in 1693. 5 Arnauld writes to the Landgraf : — i I find in these thoughts so many things which alarm me and at which almost all men, if I am not mistaken, will be so shocked, that I do not see what use there could be in a writing which apparently will be rejected by everybody ' (G. ii. 15). Leibniz felt this very keenly ; but Arnauld made ample explanations and apologies in a letter to Leibniz himself. (G. ii. 25.) NEW SYSTEM 299 most generous and exemplary way ; and having approved a number of my propositions, he praetermitted his cen- sure as regards the others, to which he was still unable to agree. Since that time I have continued my medi- tations, as I had opportunity, in order that I might give to the public only well-tested opinions, and I have also endeavoured to meet the objections raised against my essays on Dynamics, which have some connexion with this6. And in short, as some people of consideration have desired to see my opinions7 more elucidated, I have ventured upon these meditations, although they are by no means popular nor such as to be relished by every kind of mind. I have been led to this mainly in order that I may profit by the judgment of those who are en- lightened in these matters ; since it would be too trouble- some a task to seek out and call to my aid individually those who might be disposed to give me suggestions, which I shall always be glad to receive, provided they are marked by a love of truth rather than by a passion for preconceived opinions 8. 2. Although I am one of those who have worked much at mathematics, I have none the less meditated upon philosophy from my youth up ; for it always seemed to me that there was a possibility [moyen] of establishing something solid in philosophy by clear demonstrations. I had penetrated far into the country of the Scholastics, when mathematics and modern authors brought me out again, while I was still quite young. The beauty of their mechanical explanations of nature charmed me, 6 Leibniz's principal essay on Dynamics is the Specimen Dyna- micum, published in the Acta Eruditorum for April, 1695. (Gr. Math, vi. 234.) 7 The First Draft has in addition the words: 'Which they think may be useful in harmonizing faith with reason as regards matters of importance.' 8 ' I desire objections to be made against me, which oblige me to go beyond what I have already said. Objections of this kind are instructive and I like them because I may profit by them and make others profit by them ; but it is not easy to make them.' Lettre a Masson (1716) (G. vi. 629). 300 NEW SYSTEM and I rightly contemned the method of those who make use only of forms and faculties, from which we learn nothing9. But afterwards, having tried to go deeply into mechanical principles themselves, in order to find a reason for the laws of nature which experience makes known, I perceived that the mere consideration of an extended mass is not sufficient and that use must also be made of the notion of force, which is very intelligible, though it belongs to the sphere of metaphysics10. It appeared to me also that the view of those who trans- form or degrade the lower animals into mere machines, although it seems possible, is improbable and indeed is contrary to the order of things. 3. At first, when I had freed myself from the yoke of Aristotle, I took to the void and the atoms, for that is the view which best satisfies the imagination. But having got over this, I perceived, after much medita- tion, that it is impossible to find the principles of a real unity in matter alone, or in that which is only passive, since it is nothing but a collection or aggregation of parts ad infinitum". Now a multiplicity [multitude] can derive its reality only from genuine units [unites] which come from elsewhere and are quite other than the mathematical points which are only extremities of the extended and 9 See Introduction, Part i. p. 3, and Part iv. p. 156. 10 The meaning is that, although force is not anything that can be pictured or represented in imagination, it can nevertheless be quite well understood. The notion of force is ' metaphysical, ' because force is not merely a physical thing that can be perceived in the same way as other physical things. For instance, we can understand, but we cannot perceive, the potential energy of a mass. In the First Draft, Leibniz says : ' By force or power [jpuissance] I do not mean the power [powroi'r] or mere faculty, which is nothing but a near possibility of acting and which, being as it were dead, never produces an action without being stimulated from without, but I mean something between power to act [pouwir] and action, something which includes an effort, an actual working [acfe], an entelechy, for force passes of itself into action, in so far as nothing hinders it. Wherefore I regard force as constitutive of substance, since it is the source [principe~] of action, which is the characteristic of substance ' (G. iv. 472). 11 Cf. Introduction, Part ii. p. 23. NEW SYSTEM 301 modifications 12, of which it is certain that the continuous [continuum] cannot be composed 13. Accordingly, in order to find these real units [unites] I was constrained to have recourse to a real and animated point, so to speak, or to an atom of substance which must contain some kind of form or active principle, so as to make a complete being u. It was, then, necessary to recall and, as it were, to rehabili- tate the substantial forms 15, which are so much decried now-a-days, but in a way which renders them intelligible and separates the use to which they should be put from the abuse which they have suffered. I found, then, that the nature of the substantial forms consists in force, and that from this follows something analogous to feeling [sentiment] and desire [appetit] ; and that thus they must be conceived after the manner of the notion we have of souls 16. But as the soul ought not to be used to explain in detail the structure of the animal's body, I held that similarly these forms must not be used to solve the par- ticular problems of nature, although they are necessary for establishing true general principles 17. Aristotle calls them first entelechies. I call them (in a way that may 12 That is, not independent beings, but properties or relations, like the two ends of a stick. 13 E. reads : l quite other than the points of which it is cer- tain,' &c. See Prefatory Note. 14 E. reads : ' I was constrained to have recourse to a formal atom, since a material being cannot be at once material and perfectly indivisible or possessed of a genuine unity/ 15 Substantial forms as distinct from accidental forms, the former being used to explain substances, the latter to explain their accidents. 16 The transition from point to point is here rather rapid. The analogy between desire and force is manifest, but that between feeling and force is more obscure. The essence of feeling, accord- ing to Leibniz, is not consciousness but the representation or concentration of many in one ; and similarly the manifold actions of any substance are ' enveloped ' or potentially contained in its force or vital principle. Cf. Monadology, §§13 sqq. 17 In the First Draft, Leibniz says : ' In my opinion everything in nature takes place mechanically, and to give an exact and complete explanation of any particular phenomenon (such,- for instance, as weight or elasticity), nothing but figure and motion need be used' (G. iv. 472.) 302 NEW SYSTEM perhaps be more easily understood) primary forces1*, which contain not only actuality [Vacte] or the comple- ment of possibility, but also an original activity. 4. I saw that those forms and those souls, as well as our mind [esprit], ought to be indivisible, and in fact I remembered that this was the opinion of St. Thomas with regard to the souls of the lower animals19. But this truth 20 renewed the great difficulty about the origin and the duration of souls and forms. For, as every simple*1 substance which has a genuine unity can have a beginning and an end only by miracle, it follows that they can come into being only by creation and come to an end only by annihilation22. Thus I was obliged to recognize that (with the exception of the souls which God still intends specially to create) the constitutive forms of substances must have been created with the world and must always continue to exist23. So some of the Scholastics, like Albertus Magnus and John Bacon, had an inkling of part of the truth regarding the origin of these forms 24. And all this ought not to appear ex- 18 ' To distinguish it from the secondary, which is called moving force, and which is an accidental limitation or variation of primary force.' First Draft (G-. iv. 473). 19 Possibly Leibniz refers to the passage in which Aquinas says : ' The substantial form, which requires diversity in the parts, for instance the soul and especially the soul of complete animals, does not stand in exactly the same relation to the whole and to the parts. And hence it is not divided per accidensj that is to say, by a quantitative division.' Summa Theol. i. qu. 76, art. 8. Elsewhere, however, Aquinas says : ' The sensitive soul in the lower animals is corruptible ; but in man, since it is the same in substance as the rational soul, it is incorruptible.' De Anima, art. 14 ad primum. 20 Janet reads cette nouveaute, ' this new view,' instead of cette verite. 21 E. omits ' simple.' 22 The First Draft has in addition the words : * brought about expressly by the supreme power of God ' (G. iv. 474). 23 Cf. Principles of Nature and of Grace, § 6 ; Monadology, §§ 4, 5, 6, and 76. The First Draft has : ' genuine unity is absolutely in- dissoluble ' (G. iv. 474). 2* Cf. Monadology, note 116. The statement of Leibniz is so vague that one can hardly fix the passage in Albertus Magnus of which he is thinking. In his Summa de Creaturis (part ii. qu. 16, art. 3), Albertus Magnus says : ' We hold that the souls of the NEW SYSTEM 303 traordinary, for we are only attributing to forms the duration which the G-assendists 25 accord to their atoms. 5. Nevertheless I held that we must not include among these, without distinction (or confound with other forms or souls26), minds [esprits] or rational souls, which are of a higher rank and have incomparably more perfection than those forms which are sunk in matter, which in my opinion are to be found everywhere 27, and lower animals and plants are educed from the matter of the seed through generation. But if it be asked whether they are in the seed or not, we say that they are there in one way, and in another way they are not. . . . They are not there actually [actu], but they are there in the potency [potentia] of the efficient cause and the matter [efficientis et materiae]. And if it be asked : What is this efficient cause ? Is it the soul or not ? We say . . . that it is not the soul. . . .' Cf. De Animalibus (xvi. n) : 'The principle of life is in the seed in the way in which the act is in the instruments of the act. . . . And in this way also the soul is in the seed like an act and not like the entelechy of an organic body. . . . That which is in the seed is something of the soul [aliquid animate] and not the soul.' See also De Anima, bk. i. Tract. 2, cap. 13: 'The soul is indivisible, and nothing can be cut off from it.' John Bacon or Bacho, is better known as John Baconthorp, from the place in Norfolk where he was born towards the close of the thirteenth century. He was a Carmelite monk and a schoolman, and in 1329 he became Provincial of the English Carmelites. He lived much in Oxford and Paris, where he obtained a great reputation for learning. He was called the Kesolute Doctor. He died in 1346. Besides a book on the rule of his order, his chief work is the Commentaria seu quaestiones in quatuor libros Sententiarum. Leibniz probably refers to a passage in this book, In Secundum, Dist. xii. Qu. i, Art. 3, § 3. 35 Pierre Gassendi (1592-1655), a French priest and a disciple of Bacon, expounded the doctrines of Epicurus and endeavoured to adapt them to the conditions of modern thought. His attitude was both anti- Scholastic and anti-Cartesian. He severely criticized Descartes's Meditations and thus began a long controversy with Descartes regarding the origin of knowledge, Gassendi taking a purely experiential standpoint as against Descartes's belief in innate ideas. See Descartes, Meditations, Cinquiemes Objections (by Gassendi). Gassendi himself does not attribute eternity to his atoms, which he regards as created by God. The spirit of his thinking is well expressed in his own words: 'The shadow of truth which I everywhere pursue suffices to fill me with joy. I say "the shadow," for, as to truth itself, God alone can know it.' Lettre a Golius. 26 This clause within brackets is given by G., but not by E. 27 ' Which in my opinion are to be found everywhere ' is given by G., but not by E. Cf. Monadology, §§65 sqq. 304 NEW SYSTEM in comparison with which minds or rational souls are like little gods, made in the image of God and having within them some ray of the Divine enlightenment \lumieres]. For this reason God governs minds [esprits] as a prince governs his subjects, and indeed as a father looks after his children ; while, on the other hand, He deals with other substances as an engineer works with his machines. Thus minds \esprits] have special laws which put them above the revolutions of matter through the very order which God has put in them 28 ; and it may be said that everything else is made only for them, these revolutions themselves being arranged for the felicity of the good and the punishment of the wicked 29. 6. However, to return to ordinary forms or material souls™, the duration which must be attributed to them (in place of that which used to be attributed to atoms) might lead to a doubt whether they do not go from body to body; which would be metempsychosis, something almost analogous to the transmission of motion and the transmission of species 31 which certain philosophers have maintained. But this fancy is very far from the nature of things. There is no such passing32. And here the transformations noted by MM. Swammerdam, Malpighi, and Leuwenhoek 33, who are among the most excellent 28 i Through the very order which God has put in them ' is given by G., but not by E. 29 Cf. Monadology, §§ 83, 84, 89. 30 E. has dmes materieUes while G. has dmes brutes. Leibniz prob- ably wrote brutes in order to avoid the ambiguity of the other expression, which seems to suggest that some souls are 'material,' while Leibniz, of course, holds that all are 'immaterial.' By ' material or brute souls ' he means the souls which are ' sunk in matter' (§ 5), i.e. unconscious souls, in which matter as a phenomenon is bene fundatum. 31 i. e. transference of quality from one body to another, as when the quality of the leaven is imparted to the whole lump or the red colour of a drop of wine is diffused throughout water. Cf. Monadology, note 10. 32 The First Draft says : ' This transmigration of souls is an absurdity. The principles of substance do not flutter outside of substances ' (G. iv. 474). 33 ipjie reference is to such changes as that from caterpillar to NEW SYSTEM 305 observers of our time, have come to my aid and have led me the more readily to admit that no animal nor any other organic substance comes into existence at the time at which we think it does, and that its apparent genera- tion is only a development and a kind of growth [aug- mentation]. I have noticed also that the author of the Eecherche de la Verite™, M. Eegis85, M. Hartsoeker 36, butterfly. 'God has preformed things, so that new organisms are nothing but a mechanical consequence of a preceding organic constitution ; as when butterflies come from silkworms, which M. Swammerdam has shown to be merely a process of develop- ment/ The'odicee, Preface (E. 476 a ; G. vi. 41) ; cf. Monadology, § 74. John Swammerdam (1637-1680), of Amsterdam, is famous as an observer of insect life. Marcello Malpighi (1628-1694), of Bologna, the famous anatomist, is probably mentioned by Leibniz because of his work on the process of incubation. Anton van Leuwenhoek (1632-1723), of Delft, did much to support Harvey's theory of the circulation of the blood. Leibniz refers to him on account of his investigations regarding spermatozoa, in connexion with which he may be regarded as one of the founders of the science of embryology. 31 Nicolas Malebranche (1638-1715) published his De la Recherche de la Verite in 1674. Descartes had already given a similar title to one of his writings. While differing greatly from Malebranche's general theory, Leibniz endeavours to harmonize Malebranche's view with his own on many particular points. See Foucher de Careil, Lettres et opuscules inedils de Leibniz, Introduction. Leibniz corresponded intermittently with Malebranche upon philosophical and other questions between 1674 and 1711. In his Recherche de la Verite, bk. ii. ch. 7, § 3 ((Euvres, Jules Simon's ed., vol. iii. pp. 199 sqq.), Malebranche xises expressions which indicate a belief in the theory of preformation. 35 Pierre Sylvain Regis or Leroy (Petrus Silvanus Eegius) (1632-1707) was an exponent of the philosophy of Descartes, which, in opposition to the idealism of Malebranche, he developed in an empirical direction. Descartes, however, disowned the views of Regis. See (Euvres de Descartes (ed. Cousin), vol. x. p. 70. Cf. "Veitch, Method &c. of Descartes, note vi. on Innate Ideas. Cf. Kuno Fischer, Descartes and his School, bk. iii. ch. 2. Regis, whose philo- sophical school at Paris was in 1675 closed by Archbishop Harlay on account of its Cartesian teaching, wrote a violent attack upon Leibniz, charging him with injustice towards Descartes. This attack, anonymously published, will be found, along with Leibniz's reply, in E. 140 ; G: iv. 333. ^ Nicolas Hartsoeker (1656-1725) was a Dutch physicist, whose earlier work had mainly to do with the making of microscopes and telescopes. Leibniz, writing to Des Bosses in 1709, calls him vir clarissimus in Dioptricis (E. 461 a ; G. ii. 377). In 1694 Hartsoeker published an atomist philosophy of nature, based on the sup- 306 NEW SYSTEM and other able men have not been very far from this opinion. 7. But there still remained the greater question, what becomes of these souls or forms at the death of the animal or on the destruction of the individual, of the organic substance ? This is a most perplexing question, inasmuch as there seems little reason in thinking that souls remain uselessly in a chaos of confused matter37. Accordingly I came to the conclusion that there is only one view that can reasonably be taken, namely, that which affirms the conservation not only of the soul but also of the animal itself and its organic mechanism ; although the destruction of its grosser parts has reduced it to a minuteness which makes it as little perceptible to our senses as it was before its birth 38. Thus no one can exactly note the real time of death, which for a time may be taken for a mere suspension of perceptible activities and which at bottom is never anything else than this in the case of mere animals : witness the re- suscitation of flies which have been drowned and then buried in powdered chalk, and several similar instances which are sufficient to inform us that there might be other resuscitations, even when the destruction of the organic substance had gone much farther, if men were in a position to reconstruct the [animal] mechanism39. And apparently it was about something like this that the great Democritus spoke (thorough atomist as he was), though Pliny laughs at what he said 40. Accord- position of perfectly hard atoms in a perfect fluid. In 1704 he became Professor of Mathematics and Physics at Diisseldorf, and from 1706 to 1712 he discussed his philosophy of nature with Leibniz in a correspondence to which Leibniz frequently refers in his letters to Des Bosses. The correspondence is given by Gerhardt, iii. 483. Cf. Third Explanation of the New System, p. 334. 87 That is, matter which is (comparatively) inorganic. 38 Cf. Monadology, §§73 and 77. 39 Cf. Monadology, § 14, note 23 and § 21 ; Principles of Nature and of Grace, §§ 6 and 12. 40 Cf. Lettre a des Naizeaux (1711) (E. 676 b ; G. vii. 535) : 'Plato believed that material things are in a perpetual flux, but that NEW SYSTEM 307 ingly it is natural that an animal, having always been living and organic (as some people of great penetration are beginning to recognize), should likewise always re- main so. And thus, since an animal has no first birth or entirely new begetting [generation], it follows that it will have no final extinction or complete death, in the strict metaphysical sense, and that consequently, in place of the transmigration of souls, there is nothing but a transformation of one and the same animal, according as its organs are differently enfolded [plies] and more or less developed 41. 8. Nevertheless rational souls follow much higher laws and are exempt from everything which could make them lose the rank [la qualite] of citizens of the society of spirits [esprits] ; God having provided for this so care- fully that all the changes of matter cannot make them lose the moral qualities of their personality. And it may be said that everything tends to the perfection, not only of the universe in general, but also of these created genuine substances continue to exist. By "genuine substances" he appears to have meant only souls. But perhaps Democritus, thorough atomist as he was, believed in the conservation of the animal also. For he taught that there is resuscitation [reviviscence'], as Pliny says of him : reviviscendi promissa Democrito vanitas, qui ipse non revixit' [the false opinion of a coming to life again, put forth by Democritus, who himself did not come to life again]. 'We hardly know anything about this great man, except what has been borrowed from him by Epicurus, who was not capable of always taking his best things.' The words quoted from Pliny- occur in his Historia Naturalis, bk. vii. cap. 55. (Sillig's ed., vol. ii. p. 60.) u Monadology, §§72 and 73. In the First Draft (G-. iv. 474) Leibniz writes : ' As the minuteness of organic bodies may be infinite (which may be seen from the fact that their seeds, enclosed in one another, contain enfolded a continual succession of organized and animate bodies), it is easily seen that even fire, which is the most penetrating and violent agent, will not destroy an animal, since it will at most reduce it to such a smallness that fire can no longer act upon it/ In the correspondence with Arnauld, to which Leibniz refers in § i of the New System, Arnauld had asked (as an objection to Leibniz's theory of the indestruc- tibility of animals) what became of the ram which Abraham sacrificed in place of Isaac. The foregoing passage contains in brief Leibniz's answer. X 2 308 NEW SYSTEM beings in particular, which are destined to such a degree of happiness that the universe is concerned in it, in virtue of the Divine goodness which is imparted to each, so far as supreme wisdom can allow. 9. As to the ordinary body42 of animals and other corporeal substances, which have hitherto been supposed to suffer total extinction and whose changes are de- pendent rather upon mechanical rules than upon moral laws, I observed with pleasure that the author of the book De Diaeta (which is attributed to Hippocrates43) had some inkling of the truth, when he expressly said that animals are not born and do not die and that the things which we suppose to come into being and perish merely appear and disappear. This was also the opinion of Parmenides and of Melissus according to Aristotle 44 ; for these men of old had more worth than we suppose. 10. I am as ready as man can be to do justice to the moderns, yet I think they have carried reform too far ; among other things, in confounding natural with arti- 42 G. has corps ordinaire. E. reads cours ordinaire ('usual history '). 43 Hippocrates, 'the father of medicine/ is no longer regarded as the author of the De Diaeta (trepl Siairr/^. The passage to which Leibniz refers is most probably the following : dir6\\vTat ptv vvv ovo€V 6.TravT(av xpr/fMTcav, ov8e yiverai o n pri KOI irpoaOev r/v . . . aal OVTC, el faov, atroOaveiv olov re, et /«) ueTa irdvTcav TTOV yap diroOaveiTai ; oijTf T& fj.rj ov yeveaOai' ir60ev yap fffrai ; dAA.' avgerai -navra fifiovrat teal I? TO fj.r}Kto~Tov KOI [Is TO^ kXa-^iarov^ rcav y€ Svvaraiv, i. 4. 'Now none among all things is destroyed, and there does not come into being that which was not in existence before. . . . And neither is it possible for an animal to die, except along with all things (for how shall it die ?) ; nor can that which is not come into being (for whence shall it be?); but all things grow and diminish to the greatest and to the least that is possible.' See Bywater, Heraditi Ephesii Reliquiae, Appendix ii. 4t De Cae'o, F I, 298^ 14: of ft€v yap avrSiv o\cos avetXov yevtaiv Kai s, d\\' ov <}>vffiKu>s ye 8ef VOftiffVU \eyeiv. Cf. Monadology, § 74, note 116. But the views of Parmenides and Melissus, who deny the reality of change or of becoming, are very far removed from the position of Leibniz. They deny change or becoming of TO tv, not of each of a plurality of substances. NEW SYSTEM 309 ficial things, through not having great enough ideas of the majesty of nature. They think that the difference between nature's machines and ours is only a difference of size. This has lately led a very able man45 (the author of the Entretiens sur la pluralite des Mondes 46) to say that, when we look closely at nature, we find it less wonderful [admirable] than we had thought, it being merely a kind of workshop. It seems to me that this is to give an idea of nature which is not quite just nor worthy of it47, and that it is only our system which shows how real and immense after all is the distance between the least productions and mechanisms that are made by the Divine wisdom and the greatest artistic masterpieces of a limited mind [esprit] — the difference being not merely one of degree, but even one of kind. Accordingly it is to be observed that the machines of nature have a really infinite number of organs 48 and are so well equipped and so proof against all accidents that it is not possible to destroy them. A natural machine still remains a machine in its smallest parts, and moreover 45 Bernard le Bovier de Fontenelle (1657-1757), a nephew of Pierre Corneille, was secretary of the Acade'wie des Sciences at Paris from 1699 to 1741. One of his duties as secretary was to prepare every year filoges or tributes to the memory of those members of the academy who had died during the year, and among the ablest of these papers is his Eloge de Leibniz, published in the Histoire de I' Academic Royale des Sciences de Paris, anne'e 1716. He wrote a great deal of indifferent verse ; but his main work consisted in the popularizing of scientific ideas. There is a saying of his (which sounds like a parody of Leibniz) that 'everything is possible, and everybody is right/ *" 'Conversations on the Plurality of Worlds.' This book (pub- lished 1686) was intended to popularize the astronomical theories of Copernicus. It has been several times translated into English. 47 E. has merely 'which is not worthy of it.' 48 A machine made by man has a finite number of ' organs ' or parts having each a definite function in relation to the whole. The tooth of a wheel is an < organ ' of the wheel and of the whole machine. But the material particles which make up this tooth are not 'organs' of the wheel or the machine. Nature, on the other hand, is organic throughout : no part of it is not an 'organ ' of the whole. Thus a natural machine has 'a really infinite number of organs.' Cf. Monadology, § 64. 310 NEW SYSTEM it always remains the same machine it originally was, being merely transformed through different foldings [plis] it receives, and sometimes expanded, sometimes contracted and, as it were, concentrated, when we think that it is lost. ii. Further, by means of the soul or form, there is a real unity which corresponds to what in us is called the Ego ; but this cannot be the case in regard to the machines of art or to mere material mass, however well organized it may be, which can be considered only as an army or a flock, or as a pond full of fish49, or as a watch com- posed of springs and wheels. Nevertheless if there were no real substantial units [unites] there would be nothing substantial or real in the collection. It was this that compelled M. Cordemoi 50 to give up .Descartes and to adopt Democritus's doctrine of atoms in order to find a real unit [unite]. But atoms of matter are contrary to reason, besides being still composed of parts, since the invincible attachment of one part to another (even if it could rationally be conceived or supposed) would not 49 '"When I say "I," I speak of one substance only; but an army, a flock, a pond full of fish, even though it were frozen and had become solid with all the fish in it, will always be a collection of several substances.' First Draft (G. iv. 473). Cf. Introduction, Part iii. pp. 96-98. 50 Ge"raud de Cordemoi (born early in the seventeenth century, died 1684"), a French Cartesian, arrived independently at an Occasionalist position, about the same time as Geulincx developed his more famous system. See Kuno Fischer, Descartes and his School, bk. iii. ch. 2. His most important philosophical work is Le discerne- ment du corps et de I'dme (1666), and it was in this book that he so far gave up Descartes as to adopt a theory of atoms. Cf. Leibniz's Lettre a la Princesse Sophie (1705) (G. vii. 561) : 'M. Cordemoi, seeing that compound things must be the result of simple things, was forced, Cartesian though he was, to have recourse to atoms, abandoning his master. . . .' Also Lettre a Arnauld (1686) (G. ii. 78) : ' M. Cordemoi ... in order to account for the substantial unity in bodies, felt obliged to admit atoms or indivisible extended bodies in order to find something fixed to constitute a simple being. . . . He appears to have recognized something of the truth, but he had not yet seen in what the real notion of a substance consists.' Cordemoi, however, was more devoted to history than to philo- sophy. NEW SYSTEM 31 1 make one part any the less different from another51. Only atoms of substance, that is to say real units [unites] absolutely devoid of parts, are the sources of actions, and the absolute first principles of the composition of things and, as it were, the ultimate elements in the analysis of substantial things 52. They might be called metaphysical points ; they have something of the nature of life and they have a kind of perception, and mathematical points are their points of view53 for expressing the universe. But when a corporeal substance is contracted, all its organs together make but one physical point for us54. Thus physical points are only apparently indivisible. Mathematical points are indivisible [exacts], but they are only modalities. None but metaphysical or substantial points (consisting of forms or souls) are indivisible [m*c£] and real ; and without them nothing would be real, since without genuine units [unites] there would be no multi- plicity 55. 12. Having settled these things, I thought I had gained my haven, but when I set myself to meditate upon the union of soul and body I was as it were driven back into the deep sea. For I found no way of explaining how the body transmits anything to the soul or vice versa, nor how one substance can communicate with another created substance. So far as can be gathered from his writings, M/ Descartes gave this up56; but his disciples, 61 See Introduction, Part ii. p. 30. 52 E. reads * substances/ In the First Draft, Leibniz says : ' What constitutes corporeal substance must be something which corresponds to what is called ego in us, which is indivisible and nevertheless active [agissant], for being indivisible and without parts, it will no longer be a being by aggregation, but being active [agissant] it will be something substantial ' (GK iv. 473). 53 E. reads 'point of view.' Mathematical points are merely positions in space, and when we speak of positions in space, we are describing in a confused way the essential differences between Monads. Cf. Monadology, §§ 60-62. 54 Cf. Monadology, §§68 and 69. 65 Cf. Introduction, Part ii. pp. 28 sqq. 66 < The human mind is not capable of distinctly conceiving the difference of essence between soul and body and, at the same time, 312 NEW SYSTEM seeing that the common opinion is inconceivable, held that we are aware of the qualities of bodies, because God makes thoughts arise in the soul on occasion of the motions of matter ; and, on the other hand, when our soul wishes to move the body, they hold that it is God who moves the body for it. And as communication of motions also appeared to them inconceivable, they were of opinion that God gives motion to a body on occasion of the motion of another body. This is what is called the system of occasional causes, which has been brought into wide repute by the excellent reflexions of the author of the Recherche de la Verite 57. 13. It must be admitted that they have gone far into the difficulty in telling us what cannot take place ; but they do not appear to have removed it by their explana- tion of what actually does happen. It is quite true that one created substance has, in the strict metaphysical sense, no real influence upon another, and that all things and all their reality are continually produced by the power [vertu^ of God. But to solve problems it is not enough to make use of a general cause and to introduce what is called Deus ex machina. For to do this, without offering any other explanation which can be derived from the order of secondary causes, is just to have recourse *to miracle. Ill philosophy wre must endeavour to give a reason for things by showing how they are carried out by the Divine wisdom in conformity with the notion of the matter we are dealing with58. 14. Accordingly, being obliged to admit that it is im- their union, for it would then be necessary to conceive both as a single being and at the same time as two different things, which .is a contradiction.' (Euvres (ed. Cousin), vol. ix. p. 132. 57 Arnold Geulincx (1625-1669) was the real founder of Occa- sionalism. The first part of his Ethica appeared in 1665, while Malebranche's great work was published in 1674. See Introduction, Part ii. pp. 42 sqq. Cf. Kuno Fischer, Descartes and his School, bk. iii. ch. 3. 58 We must not make a vague reference to the Divine wisdom, but must show how it is present in particular departments of experience. NEW SYSTEM 313 possible the soul or any other real substance should receive anything from outside, unless through the Divine omni- potence, I was insensibly led to an opinion which surprised me, but which seems inevitable and which, in fact, has very great advantages and very considerable beauties. It is this, that God at first so created the soul, or any other real unity, that everything must arise 59 in it from its own inner nature [fonds] with a perfect spontaneity as regards itself and yet with a perfect con- formity to things outside of it. And thus our inner feelings [sentiments] (that is to say, those which are in the soul itself and not in the brain or in the finer parts of the body), being only connected phenomena of external things or rather genuine appearances and, as it were, well-ordered dreams60, these internal perceptions in the soul itself must come to it from its original constitution, that is to say from the representative nature (capable of expressing beings outside of it in relation to its organs 61) which was given to it at creation and which constitutes its individual character. And accordingly, since each of these substances accurately represents the whole universe in its own way and from a certain point of view, and the perceptions or expressions of external things come into the soul at their appropriate time, in virtue of its own laws, as in a world 6'2 by itself and as if there existed nothing but God and the soul (to adopt the phrase of a certain person of high intellectual power, renowned for his piety63), there will be a perfect agreement between all these substances, which will have the same result as would be observed if they had communication with one * 59 E. has 'arises.' As to the 'spontaneity* of the soul and its 'creation,' see Monadology, § 47, note 75. 60 ' And so genuine that they can be successfully foreseen.' First Draft (G. iv. 477). See Introduction, Part iii. p. 98 sqq. 61 That is, according to the nature and disposition of its organs. 62 E. has 'the world.' 63 Kirchmann suggests that this may perhaps refer to Foucher. But Leibniz uses the phrase, without any special reference or acknowledgment, in a letter to Foucher, written in 1686. (G. i. 382.) 314 NEW SYSTEM another by a transmission of species or of qualities, such as the mass of ordinary philosophers suppose Gi. Further, as the organized mass, in which is the point of view of the soul, is more nearly expressed by the soul65 and, conversely, is ready of itself to act, according to the laws of the corporeal mechanism, at the moment the soul desires it, without either of them interfering with the laws of the other — the animal spirits \les esprits] 66 and the blood having exactly at that moment the right motions to correspond to the passions and perceptions of the soul — this mutual relationship, prearranged in each substance in the universe, produces what we call their communication and alone constitutes the union of soul and ~body. And in this way we can understand how the soul has its seat in the body through an immediate presence, which is as near as possible, since the soul is in the body as the unit [unite] is in the multiplicity which is the resultant of units [unites] 67. 6* See Monadology, § 7, note 10. 65 E. omits ' by the soul' (par elle). 66 'Animal spirits ' was the name given by Descartes to certain ' very fine particles of the blood,' by means of which he explained muscular movement. The name was derived from the Stoic Trvevfta, through the early medical philosophers, such as Galen, who speaks of l natural spirits ' and ' vital spirits ' ; but Descartes's use of the term is original. * What I here call " spirits " are only bodies, and they have no other property except that they are very small bodies which move very quickly, like the particles of flame which come from a lighted torch ; so that they do not stay in any place, and as soon as some of them enter the cavities of the brain, others go out again through the pores in its substance, which pores lead them to the nerves and thence to the muscles, by means of which they move the body in all the different ways it can be moved.' Les Passions de I'Ame, part i. art. 10. See also articles 11-13, and Method, part v, where he says that the ' animal spirits ' are ' like a very subtle wind, or rather a very pure and vivid flame.' The name survives in common language, and the hypothesis was only set aside by the results of microscopic study in anatomy. Cf. Kuno Fischer, Descartes and his School, bk. ii. ch. 9, § a. 67 Descartes also held that the soul must be present to the whole organism. But he maintained that ' nevertheless there is in the body a part in which the soul exercises its functions more specially than in any other part,' this special 'seat of the soul' being the pineal gland in the brain. (Les Passions, part i. articles 30-33.) NEW SYSTEM 315 15. This hypothesis is very possible. For why might not God in the beginning give to substance an inner nature or force which could regularly produce in it — as in an automaton that is spiritual or endowed with a living principle c8, but free in the case of a substance which partakes of reason 69 — everything that will happen to it, that is to say, all the appearances or expressions it will have, and that without the help of any created thing ? This is the more likely since the nature of sub- stance necessarily requires and essentially involves a progress or change, without which it would have no force to act70. And as the nature of the soul is to represent the universe in a very exact way (though with greater or less distinctness), the succession of representa- tions which the soul produces for itself will correspond naturally to the succession of changes in the universe itself ; while, on the other hand, the body has also been adapted to the soul to fit the circumstances in which the soul is conceived as acting outwardly. This adaptation of the body to the soul is the more reasonable inasmuch as bodies are made only for spirits [esprits] 71, which alone are capable of entering into fellowship with God and celebrating His glory. Thus as soon as we see that this hypothesis of agreements [accords']™ is possible, we see Leibniz seeks to show that, on his hypothesis, the connexion between soul and body is much closer. The soul is ' immediately ' present to the body and thus has no special seat but is in every part (independently of the part's position) as the unit is in every part of the whole. 68 The French is : un automate spiritual ou formel. Formel conveys the idea of the form or individual unity of the thing, as in the phrase ' substantial form.' 69 Every substance has spontaneity, inasmuch as it produces from within itself the series- of its states or phenomena ; but rational souls alone have liberty, for liberty is action under the guidance of right reason. 70 No substance can act upon anything outside of it. Thus its action must appear in some internal change. 71 That is to say, bodies are entirely subordinate to spirits, as the realm of efficient causes is to that of final causes. See Monadology, concluding §§. 72 In the First Draft, Leibniz says : < I call this the system of 31 & NEW SYSTEM also that it is the most reasonable hypothesis and that it gives a wonderful idea of the harmony of the universe and the perfection of the works of God. 1 6. There is also this great advantage in our hypo- thesis, that instead of saying that we are free only apparently and enough for practical purposes, as several clever people have held, we must rather say that we are only apparently constrained, and that, to use strict meta- physical language, we possess a perfect independence as regards the influence of all other created things 73. This also throws a wonderful light upon the immortality of our soul and the ever unbroken preservation of our individuality, which is perfectly well-ordered by its own nature and independent of all external contingencies, whatever appearance there may be to the contrary. Never has any system more completely shown our high calling. Every spirit [esprit] being like a world apart, sufficient to itself, independent of eveiy other created thing, involving the infinite, expressing the universe, is as lasting, as continuous in its existence and as absolute as the very universe of created things. Thus we should hold that each spirit should always play its part \_faire figure] in the universe in the way that is most fitted to contribute to the perfection of the society of all spirits, which constitutes their moral union in the City of God. There is also here a new and surprisingly clear proof of the existence of God. For this perfect agreement of so many substances which have no communication with one another can come only from their common cause 74. 17. In addition to all these advantages which this correspondence' (G-. iv. 476). He is still feeling for the name ' Pre-established Harmony,' which he uses for the first time in the First Explanation of the New System (1696). 73 See Introduction, Part iii. pp. 141 sqq. 74 In the First Draft, Leibniz says : ' It is true that this is only by a participation, though limited, in the Divine perfections ; for the agreement among the effects arises from their expressing the common cause' (G-. iv. 475). Cf. Principles of Nature and of Grace, § n, note 49. NEW SYSTEM 317 hypothesis has in its favour, it may be said that it is something more than' a hypothesis, since it hardly appears possible to explain things in any other intelli- gible way, and since several great difficulties, which have hitherto perplexed men's minds [les esprits], seem to disappear of themselves when we rightly comprehend this hypothesis. The expressions of ordinary language may also be quite well adapted to it. For we may say that the substance whose condition [disposition] explains a change in an intelligible way (so that we may hold that it is this substance to which tfre others have on this point been adapted from the beginning, according to the order of the decrees of God) is the substance which, in respect of this change, we should consequently conceive as acting upon the others75. Thus the action of one substance upon another is not an emission nor a trans- plantation of an entity as is commonly supposed, and it can be rationally understood only in the way I have just mentioned. It is true that we quite well conceive in matter both the emission and the receiving of parts through which we are entitled to explain mechanically all the phenomena of physics ; but as material mass is not a substance 76, it is evident that action as regards substance itself can only be what I have just said that it is. 1 8. These considerations, however metaphysical they may appear, are also of remarkable service in physics for establishing the laws of motion, as our Dynamics will be able to show. For it may be said that in the impact of bodies each suffers only through its own elasticity, caused by77 the motion which is already in it78. And 7r> See Introduction, Part iii. pp. 105 sqq. 76 See Introduction, Part iii. p. no. 77 E. has cause du, 'a (or the) cause of the.' G-. has cause du, ' caused by the.' The First Draft has : ' which comes from a motion already existing in it ' (G. iv. 476). 78 Leibniz opposes the idea that there is a fixed quantity of motion dispersed throughout the universe and passing indifferently 318 NEW SYSTEM as to absolute motion, nothing can determine it mathe- matically, since all ends [se termine] in relations, with the result that there is always a perfect equivalence of hypotheses as in astronomy 79 ; so that, whatever number of bodies we take, we may arbitrarily assign rest or such and such a degree of velocity to whichever we like, with- out it being possible for us to be refuted by the pheno- mena of motion, whether it be in a straight line, in a circle, or composite. Yet it is reasonable to attribute to bodies real motions, according to the supposition which explains the phenomena in the most intelligible way, for this is in harmony with the notion of activity [action] which we have here maintained80. from one body to another. Each body, he would say, has a force, which is the cause of its actual motions, and when two bodies collide, there is not a transference of motion from one to the other, but a certain release of the pent-up force in each, and this release shows itself in the elasticity of their rebound. See Introduction, Part iii. pp. 89 sqq. 79 ' Absolute motion ' would be motion that is not in any degree rest. But motion must always be determined through relation. One body has motion only in reference to another, and, accordingly, if we wish to determine which of the two really (i. e. absolutely) moves, we must refer them both to some third body and so ad infinitum. The ' equivalence of hypotheses in astronomy' probably refers to the fact that the hypothesis of Copernicus (1473-1543), according to which all the planets move round the sun, and the hypothesis of Tycho Brahe (1546-1601), according to which the sun moves round the earth and the other planets move round the sun, equally well explained the phenomena as observed at that time. Cf. G. iv. 369, and Descartes, Principia, Part iii. §§ 15-18. 80 See Appendix C, p. 204. EXPLANATION OF THE NEW SYSTEM OF THE COMMUNICATION BETWEEN SUBSTANCES, BY WAY OF REPLY TO WHAT IS SAID ABOUT IT IN THE JOURNAL OF SEPTEM- BER 12, I6951. 1696. PREFATORY NOTE. IN the Journal des Savants for September, 1695, there appeared a letter to Leibniz from Foucher in which various objections to the New System were stated. Simon Foucher (1644-1696) was a Canon of Dijon, who professed philosophical scepticism and endeavoured to restore the teaching of the later Academics, somewhat as Gassendi sought to interpret anew the doctrines of Epicurus. Between 16/6 and 1695 Leibniz corresponded with Foucher, discussing in the earlier letters questions regarding the theory of knowledge and in the later letters questions of Physics. Foucher's comparatively early death was to some extent due to overwork. In 1697 Leibniz writes to Nicaise (G. ii. 566) : ' I am grieved at the death of M. Foucher. His curiosity was limited, and was directed only to certain somewhat dry matters, and even these he did not treat with the accuracy they required. Perhaps his aim was merely to be the resuscitator of the Academics, as M. Gassendi has resuscitated the Sect of Epicurus. But he ought not to have confined himself to generalities. Plato, Cicero, Sextua Empiricus and others might have enabled him to make a real advance. And under pretext of doubting, he might have established good and useful truths. I took the liberty of giving 1 The reference is of course to the letter of Foucher in the Journal des Savants. 320 FIRST EXPLANATION him my opinion as to this ; but he had perhaps other views of which I did not know enough. Yet he had much cleverness and subtlety and he was a most virtuous man, and hence I lament him.' (Cf. G. i. 365.) Leibniz replied to the objections of Foucher in an Explanation of the Neiv System, which appeared in the Journal des Savants for April, 1696. ^A further Explana- tion (called by Erdmann the Troisieme Eclaircissement} was published in the Journal for November, 1696. I have translated these two Explanations, omitting that which Dutens and Erdmann call Second Eclaircissement (E. 133, J. S. Feb. 1696, cf. G. iv. 498), as the Troisieme Eclaircissement contains practi- cally the whole of it. In Foucher's letter of objections there appears the simile of the clocks, which Leibniz passes over in his immediate reply but takes up and develops in the Second and Third Explana- tions. Foucher writes : ' It will be granted you that God, the great Artificer of the universe, can so perfectly adjust all the organic parts of a man's body, that they may be capable of producing all the motions which the soul combined with this body will desire to produce in the course of his life, with- out the soul having the power to change these motions or to modify them in any way, and that on the other hand God can make a construction in the soul (be it a mechanism of a new kind or not), by means of which all the thoughts and modifi- cations which correspond to these motions might successively arise at the same moment in which the body performs its corresponding functions, and it will also be granted you that this is no more impossible than to make two clocks keep time [s'accorder] so well and go so uniformly that at the moment clock A strikes twelve, clock B will strike twelve also, so that we imagine the two clocks to be kept going by the same weight or the same spring' (E. 129 b ; G. iv. 488). The simile was originally applied in this way by Geulincx. See Introduction, Part ii. p. 43 note ; cf. Third Explanation of the New System, p. 331 note. In the translation of the Explanations I follow G.'s revised text (G. iv. 493, 500 sqq.). E. gives them as they were origin- ally published (E. 131, 134 sqq.). I recollect, Sir, that in compliance with what I under- stood to be your desire, I communicated to you my hypothesis in philosophy several years ago, although at OF THE NEW SYSTEM 321 the same time I indicated to you that I had not yet resolved to make it known. I asked your opinion of it in exchange ; but I do not recollect having received objections from you : otherwise, teachable [docile] as I am, I should not have caused you to offer the same objections twice over. Nevertheless they still come in time, although they come after I have published. For I am not of those with whom the committing of them- selves to an opinion takes the place of reason, as you will find when you are able to say that you have brought forward2 any precise and urgent reason against my opinions ; which apparently has not been your purpose s. Your intention was to speak as an able Academic 4, and thus to give an opportunity for a thorough investigation of things. i 6. I intended to explain here, not the principles of extension [Vetendue], but the principles of that which is actually extended [Tetendu effectif] or of bodily mass ; and these principles, in my opinion, are real unities, that is to say, substances possessing a genuine unity 6. 2. The unity of a clock, which you mention, is in my view quite other than that of an animal ; for an animal may be a substance possessing a genuine unity, like what is called ego [moi] in us ; while a clock is nothing but an aggregate [assemblage]. 3. I do not find the principle of the animal's conscious- ness \le prindpe sensitif^ in the arrangement [disposition] of its organs ; and I agree that this arrangement concerns only the bodily mass 7. a E. has < when you are able to bring forward.' 8 E. adds ' on this occasion.' * In reference to Foucher's philosophical position. See Prefatory Note. 6 In G.'s text the paragraphs are numbered. In E.'s text they are not numbered, and the paragraphs are differently divided. 6 Foucher had maintained that 'the essential principles of ex- tension cannot really exist,' i.e. that extension has no ultimate real elements. (E. 129 a ; G. iv. 487.) Cf. Appendix H, p. 329. T Foucher had said : * Whatever arrangement [disposition] the organs of an animal might have, that is not enough to make it 322 FIRST EXPLANATION 4. I notice these things in order to prevent misunder- standings, and to show that what you say on this point is by no means contrary to what I have brought forward 8. Thus it appears that you do not make me out to be wrong in requiring genuine unities, and in consequently rehabilitating the substantial forms. But when you appear to say that the soul of the lower animals must have reason, if we attribute feeling [sentiment] to it9, that is an inference10 of which I do not see the proof11. 5. With laudable candour you recognize that my hypothesis of harmony or concomitance is possible. But you still have a certain repugnance to it ; doubtless because you think that it is purely arbitrary, through not being aware that it follows from my view regarding unities ; for everything in my theory is connected to- gether. 6. Accordingly you ask, Sir, of what use is all this elaborate contrivance which I attribute to the Author of nature12 ? As if one could attribute too much contrivance to Him, and as if this exact mutual correspondence of conscious [sensible] ; for in short this has to do with nothing but the organic and mechanical structure, and I do not see that you are right in attributing to the lower animals a principle of conscious- ness, substantially different from that of men ' (E. 129 b ; G. iv. 488;. 8 E. does not have this sentence. ' Foucher wrote : l After all, it is not without ground that the Cartesians acknowledge that if we allow to the animals a principle of consciousness, capable of distinguishing good from evil, we must also, as a consequence, allow to them reason, discrimination and judgment ' (E. 129 b ; G. iv. 488). In the Remarques sur Us Objections de M. Foucher Leibniz replies : ' I do this ' [attribute to the animals a principle of consciousness, substantially different from that of men] ' because we do not find that the animals make the reflexions which constitute reason and which, producing the knowledge of necessaiy truths or science, make the soul capable of personality. The lower animals, having perception, distinguish good and evil ; but they are not capable of moral good and evil, which presuppose reason and conscience' (G. iv. 492). Cf. Honadology, §§ 25-30. 10 E. reads ' you make use of an inference.' 11 E. reads l force.' 12 Foucher's question is: 'Of what use is all this great elaborate contrivance among substances, unless to make us believe that they act upon one another, although this is not the case ? ' (E. 130 a ; G. iv. 489). OF THE NEW SYSTEM 323 substances, through the special laws which each has at the beginning received, were not a thing most admirable in itself and worthy of its Author ! You ask also what advantage I find in it. 7. I might refer to what I have already said ; but I reply, first, that when a thing cannot but be13, there is no need to ask of what use it is, before we admit it. Of what use is the incommensurability of the side with the diagonal ? 8. I reply in the second place, that this correspondence is of use in explaining the communication of substances and the union of the soul with the body, through the laws of nature which have been established from the first [par avance], without having recourse either to a transmission of species14 [qualities], which is incon- ceivable, or to a new intervention of God, which seems out of accord with the fitness of things. For it is to be observed that as there are laws of nature in matter, so there are also laws of nature in souls or forms ; and the meaning of these laws is that which I have just indicated. 9. Again, I am asked 15 whence it comes that God does not think it enough to produce all the thoughts and modifications of the soul, without these useless bodies, which the soul, it is said, can neither move nor know. The answer is easy. It was God's will that there should 13 Has Leibniz shown that his pre-established harmony ' cannot but be ' ? In the Remarques already quoted, he says : ' This elaborate contrivance, which makes each substance correspond to all others, is necessary because all substances are the effect of a supreme wisdom ; and it was not otherwise possible (at any rate in the order of nature and without miracles) to bring about their inter- dependence and the changing of one by another or in consequence of another. It nevertheless remains true that they act upon one another, provided we give a right sense to these words. . . . God is not obliged to make a system, about which we are not liable to make mistakes ; as He was not obliged to avoid the system of the earth's motion, in order to save us from the error into which almost all astronomers fell until Copernicus ' (G-. iv. 492). u See Monadology, § 7, note 10. 15 E. has ' I shall be asked.' The question was put by Foucher in his letter of objections. Y 2 324 FIRST EXPLANATION be more substances rather than fewer, and He thought it right that these modifications of the soul should corre- spond to something outside 16. 10. No substance is useless; they are all made to co-operate 17 towards fulfilling the plan of God. 11. I am also far from admitting that the soul does not know bodies, although this knowledge arises without any influence of the one upon the other. 12. I will not even shrink from saying18 that the soul moves the body ; and as a Copernican speaks truly of the rising of the sun, a Platonist of the reality of matter, and a Cartesian of the reality of sensible qualities 19, provided we rightly understand them, in the same way I hold that it is most true to say that substances act upon one another, provided we understand that one is the cause of changes in the other in consequence of the laws of the harmony. 13. The objection which is based on the supposed lethargy of bodies, which would be without activity [action] while the soul believes them to be in motion, cannot hold because of this very unfailing correspondence, which the Divine wisdom has established 20. 18 In the Eemargues Leibniz says : l Bodies were necessary so that there might be produced not only our unities and souls but also those of the other corporeal substances, animals and plants, which are in our bodies and in those which surround us' (G. iv. 493 \ This last sentence indicates Leibniz's real answer to the difficulty (the answer he would have given in later years\ viz. that ulti- mately all bodies are souls or Monads, so that to ask why there are bodies is to ask why there are other souls. Is the answer sufficient ? 17 E. has ' they all co-operate.' 18 E. has 1 1 will even raise no objection against saying.' 19 i. e. the qualities of bodies, as they are perceived by our senses. As sensations, facts of consciousness, these are real, according to Descartes ; but as qualities of bodies they are confused and there- fore unreal. See Principia, Part i. §§ 66-70. 20 Toucher says that, on Leibniz's hypothesis, ' even although no motion took place in bodies ' [in harmony with the action of the soul], ' the soul would nevertheless always think that such a motion does take place ; in the same way as sleeping people think they are moving their limbs and walking, while nevertheless their limbs OF THE NEW SYSTEM 325 14. I have no knowledge of these idle, useless, and inactive masses, to which reference is made. There is activity [action] everywhere, and I maintain it even more fully than does the received philosophy ; because I hold that there is no body without motion, no sub- stance without force [effort]*1. 15. I do not understand the nature of the objection that is contained in the words : — In truth, Sir, is it not evident that these opinions were formed with a special purpose in view, and that these systems, appearing by way of after- thought [venant apres coup], were constructed merely to safe- guard certain principles? All hypotheses are made with a special purpose in view, and all systems appear ~by way of afterthought [viennent apres coup], in order to safeguard phenomena or appearances ; but I do not see what are the principles in favour of which I am said to be prejudiced and which I wish to safeguard. 1 6. If it is meant that I am led to my hypothesis also by reasons a priori or by fixed principles, as is actually the case ; this is rather a commendation of the hypo- thesis than an objection to it. It is usually enough that a hypothesis be proved a posteriori, by being adequate to the phenomena ; but when there are in addition other reasons for it, and these a priori, it is so much the better. 1 7. But perhaps what is meant is that, having invented a new opinion, I have delighted to make use of it, rather to give myself airs because of its novelty than because I have found any usefulness in it. I am not sure, Sir, that you have so bad an opinion of me as to attribute to me these thoughts. For you know that I love truth, and that, if I were so fond of novelties, I should have more are at rest and do not move at all. So, when wide awake, souls would always continue to be persuaded that their bodies move in obedience to their volitions, though nevertheless these idle and useless masses would be inactive and would remain in a continual lethargy ' (E. 130 a ; G. iv. 489). 21 That is, force which is not necessarily observed, but includes tendency or the active potentiality of observed force. 326 FIRST EXPLANATION eagerness to produce them — especially those whose sound- ness is recognized. But, lest those who know me less should give to your words a meaning which we should not like 22, it will be enough to say, that in my opinion it is impossible otherwise to explain transeunt activity \Taction emanente] 23 in conformity with the laws of ntture, and that I thought that the use of my hypothesis would be evident, owing to the difficulty which the most able philosophers of our time have found as to the inter- relation [communication] of minds [esprits] and bodies, and even of bodily substances with one another: and I do not know but that you yourself have found some difficulty in this. 1 8. It is true that, in my view, there are forces [efforts] in all substances ; but these forces [efforts] are, rightly speaking, only in the substance itself, and what follows from them in other substances takes place only in virtue of a harmony pre-established 24 (if I may use the word), and in no wise by a real influence or by the transmission of some species or quality25. As I have explained what activity [action] and passivity [passion] are, the nature of force [effort] and of resistance may be inferred. 19. You say, Sir, that you know there are still many questions to be put, before those which we have been discussing can be decided. But perhaps you will find that I have already put these questions ; and I am not sure that your Academics have applied what is good in their method more rigorously and effectively than I26. I strongly 29 E. reads ' contrary to my intentions.' 23 That is, activity which apparently passes beyond the substance itself and has effects in other substances. It is the same thing as the ' influence ' of one substance upon another. See De ipsa Nalura (1698), § 10 (E. 157 b ; G. iv. 510), where Leibniz uses the expression transeuntes creaturarum actiones. 24 This is the first use of the term by Leibniz. 35 See Monadology, § 7, note 10. 46 Foucher wrote : ' We ought to observe the laws of the Academics, the second of which forbids us to put in question matters which we clearly see cannot be settled, as are almost all those of which we have been speaking ; not that these questions OF THE NEW SYSTEM 327 approve of seeking to demonstrate truths from first principles: it is more useful than people think, and I have often 2V put this precept in practice. Thus I com- mend what you say on this point, and I would that your example may lead our philosophers to think of it as they ought. 20. I will add a further reflexion, which seems to me helpful in making the reality and use of my system better understood. You know that M. Descartes believed in the conservation of the same quantity of motion in bodies. It has been shown that he was wrong in this ; but I have shown that it is still true that there is conservation of the same moving force, instead of which he put quantity of motion. Nevertheless, he was perplexed by the changes which take place in the body in consequence of modifications of the soul, because they seemed to break this law. But he thought he had found a way out of it (which is certainly ingenious) in saying that we must distinguish between motion and direction ; and that the soul cannot increase nor diminish the moving force, but that it changes the direction or determination of the course of the animal spirits, and that it is in this way that voluntary motions take place 28. It is true that he made no attempt to explain how the soul acts so as to change the course of bodies, for there seems as much difficulty in this as there is in saying that the soul gives motion to bodies, unless with me you have recourse to the pre-established harmony ; but it is to be observed that there is another law of nature, which I have discovered and proved, and which M. Descartes was unaware of, namely, that there is conservation not only of the same quantity of moving force, but also of the same quantity are absolutely insoluble, but because they are soluble only in a certain order, which requires that philosophers should begin by coming to an agreement as to the infallible mark of truth, and should confine themselves to demonstrations from first principles ' (E. 130 b ; G. iv. 490). 27 E. omits ' often.' Cf. Introduction, Part ii. p. 59. 28 See Monadology, § 80, note 127, and Introduction, Partiii. p. 89. 328 FIRST EXPLANATION of direction in ivhatever line [de quelque cote] 29 we take it in the ivorld. That is to say, drawing any straight line you please, and taking also such bodies and so many of them as you please, you will find that, considering all these bodies together, without omitting any of those which act upon any one of those which you have taken, there will always be the same amount [quantite] of progression in the same direction [du meme cote] in all lines parallel to the straight line you have taken — observing that the total amount of progression is to be calculated by sub- tracting from the amount of progression of the bodies which go in the given direction, the amount of progression of those which go in the opposite direction 30. This law, being as good and as general as the other, deserved as 29 E. reads vers quelque cote. 30 See Principles of Nature and of Grace, § n, note 48. Cf. Epistola ad Bernoullium (1696) (G. Math. iii. 243; E. 108 note): 'In the next place it is to be observed that I make a distinction between absolute force and directing force, although I can deduce and demonstrate directing force from the sole consideration of absolute power. And indeed I prove that there is conservation not only of the same absolute force or quantity of action in the world, but also of the same directing force and the same quantity of direction in the same lines [ad easdem paries], i.e. the same quantity of progression, its direction being taken into account and the quantity of pro- gression being counted equal to the mass multiplied by the velocity, and not by the square of the velocity' [mv, not ?nt/2]. 1 Nevertheless this quantity of progression differs from quantity of motion in this way, that when two bodies are moving in opposite directions their total quantity of motion (in the Cartesian sense) is to be got by adding together the quantity of motion of each (calculated as the mass into the velocity) ; but the quantity of progression is to be got by subtracting the one from the other ; for in such a case the difference between the quantities of motion will be the quantity of progression. Therefore when Descartes thought that he could safeguard the soul's power of acting on the body in this way, that while the soul cannot increase or diminish the quantity of motion in the world, it can nevertheless increase or diminish the quantity of direction of the [animal] spirits, he erred through not knowing this new law of ours regarding the conservation of the quantity of direction, which is no less beautiful and inviolable than the law of the conservation of absolute force [virtus'] or power of action.' The ' quantity of progression ' would now be called a projection of the quantity of motion. A full explanation, with diagrams, will be found in the appendix to Boutroux's edition of the Monadologie. APPENDIX H 329 little to be broken, and this is so, according to my system31, in which there is conservation of force and direction, and none of the natural laws of bodies are broken, notwithstanding the changes which take place in body in consequence of changes in the soul. APPENDIX H. ON THE ELEMENTS OF EXTENSION. ONE of Foucher's objections to the New System was based on the contention that extension has no ultimate real elements (E. 1 29 a ; Gr. iv. 487). In some Remarques sur les Objections de M. Foucher (G. iv. 490) Leibniz replies : ' The author of the objection does not seem to have rightly understood my view. Extension or space, and the surfaces, lines and points that can be conceived in it, are nothing but relations of order or orders of co-existence, both as regards that which actually exists and as regards the possible thing that might be put in place of that which exists. Thus they have no ultimate component elements [principes], any more than number has. And as a broken number, for instance £, can be further broken into two-fourths or four-eighths and so on ad infinitum, without our being able to reach the absolutely smallest fractions or to conceive the number as a whole formed by the combination of ultimate elements, so it is with a line which can be divided, just like this number. Again, strictly speaking, the number ^ in the abstract is a perfectly simple ratio [rapport], not at all formed by the compounding of other fractions, although in numbered things there is equality between two -fourths and one -half. And we may say as much regarding an abstract line, since compounding takes place only in concrete things, or the masses of which these abstract lines indicate the relations. And it is also in this way that mathematical points are to be regarded : they are merely modalities, that is to say extremi- ties. And as in the abstract line all is indefinite, it has reference to everything which is possible, as in the case of 31 E. reads ' and this ' [i. e. the breach of the law] ' is avoided by my system.' 330 APPENDIX H fractions of a number, without our troubling about divisions actually made, which indicate points in the line in various ways. But in actual substantial things the whole is a sum or aggregate of simple substances or rather of a multitude of real units [unites]. And it is the confounding of the ideal and the actual that has brought the whole matter into confusion and has produced the labyrinth de compositione continui. Those who have supposed the line to be made up of points have sought for the primary elements in ideal things or relations, which was quite a mistake ; and those who have found that relations like number or space (which includes the order or relation of possible co-existent things) cannot be formed by the aggregation of points, have usually made the mistake of denying the primary elements of substantial realities, as if they had no primary unities, or as if ^there were no simple substances. Nevertheless number and the line are not chimeri- cal things, although they are not thus compounded, for they are relations which involve eternal truths, in accordance with which the phenomena of nature are ordered. Hence it may be said that, considered in the abstract, \ and \ are indepen- dent of one another, or rather the total ratio [rapport] \ is anterior— in the order of reason [dans le signe de la raison], as the Scholastics say — to the partial ratio ^, since it is by the subdivision of the half that we come to the fourth, following the order of what is ideal ; and the same is the case with the line, in which the whole is anterior to the part because the part is only possible and ideal. But in realities, in which there are only divisions actually made, the whole is merely a sum or aggregate, as in the case of a flock of sheep. It is true that the number of simple substances which enter into a mass, however small it be, is infinite, since in addition to the soul which constitutes the real unity of the animal, the body of the sheep (for instance) is actually subdivided, that is to say it is also an aggregate of invisible animals or plants (which are likewise compound) besides that which constitutes also their real unity ; and although this proceeds ad infinitum, it is manifest that ultimately all is reducible to these unities, the remainder or the aggregates being merely well-founded phenomena.' THIED EXPLANATION l— EXTRACT FROM A LETTER OF M. D. L. REGARDING HIS PHILOSOPHICAL HYPOTHESIS AND THE CURIOUS PROBLEM, PROPOUNDED TO THE MATHEMATICIANS BY ONE OF HIS FRIENDS, WITH AN EXPLANATION RE- GARDING SOME DISPUTED POINTS IN PRECEDING JOURNALS BETWEEN THE AUTHOR OF.THE PRINCIPLES OF PHYSICS2 AND THE AUTHOR OF THE OBJECTIONS. 1696. SOME learned and acute friends of mine having con- sidered my new hypothesis on the great question of the union of soul and body, and having found it of value, have asked me to give some explanations regarding the objections which have been brought against it and which arose from its not having been rightly understood. I think the matter may be made intelligible to minds of every kind by the following illustration. Suppose two clocks3 or two watches which perfectly 1 E. has ' Third Explanation,' which is omitted by G. 2 Nicholas Hartsocker. ' M.D.L.' is a pseudonym of Leibniz. 3 See Prefatory Note. Geulincx's use of the simile is as follows : * My will certainly does not move the moving power that it may move my limbs ; but He who imparted motion to matter and laid down laws for it, Himself also formed my will. Therefore He bound together these most diverse things (the motion of matter and the choice of my will), so that when my will wills, such a motion as it wills occurs, and on the other hand when 332 THIRD EXPLANATION keep time together [s'accordenf]. Now that may happen in three ways. The first way consists in the mutual in- fluence of each clock upon the other ; the second, in the care of a man who looks after them ; the third, in their own accuracy. The first way, that of influence, was ascertained on trial by the late M. Huygens 4, to his great astonishment. He attached two large pendulums to the same piece of wood. The continual swinging of these pendulums imparted similar vibrations to the particles of the wood ; but as these different vibrations could not the motion occurs, the will wills it, without any causality or influence [influxes] of the one upon the other ; as in the case of two clocks which are carefully adjusted together to the daily course of the sun, as often as the one strikes and tells us the hours, the other strikes in the same way and indicates the hours, and that apart from any causality, by which the one might produce this effect in the other, but solely on account of the connexion which comes from the fact that both were made by the same art and with similar workmanship. Thus, for example, the motion of the tongue accompanies our volition to speak, and this volition accompanies that motion : and the motion does not depend upon the volition, nor the volition upon the motion, but both depend upon the same Supreme Artificer, who has so wonderfully connected and bound them together.' Ethica, Tract. I. cap. 2, § 2, note 19 ; Land's ed., vol. iii. p. 2-1 1. Cf. ibid, note 48 ; Land, iii. 220. Cf. also Introduction, Part ii. p. 43. * Christian Huygens (1629-1695) was a mathematician, phy- sicist and astronomer, who lived for the most part in Holland, where he was born, and in France, where Leibniz, coming to Paris in 1672, met him. Anticipating the revocation of the Edict of Nantes, the Protestant Huygens left Paris in 1681 and returned to Holland, but he continued to correspond with Leibniz on mathematical subjects. In 1673 Huygens published his great work Horologium OscillatQrium, sive de motu pendulorum ad horologia adaptatOj in which he gave a full account of a discovery he had made in 1656, that of the pendulum clock. Among the other great works of Huygens were discoveries in connexion with the astronomy of the planets, the undulatory theory of light, and the use of spiral springs for regulating the balances of watches. Leibniz frequently acknowledges his great indebtedness to Huygens in regard to mathematics, and in July, 1695, he writes to Nicaise : ' Nothing can equal the loss of the incomparable M. Huygens. Most certainly he ought to be named immediately after Galileo and Descartes. He might still have given us great light upon nature' (G. ii. 552). But elsewhere he says that ' M. Huygens had no taste for metaphysics.' Lettre a Eevnond (1714) (E. 702 b ; G. iii. 607). OF THE NEW SYSTEM 333 continue in their proper order, without interfering with one another, unless the pendulums kept time together, it happened, by a kind of wonder, that even when their swinging was deliberately disturbed they soon came to swing together again, somewhat like two stretched strings that are in unison. The second way of making two clocks (even though they be bad ones) constantly keep time together would be to put them in charge of a skilled workman who should keep them together from moment to moment. I call this the way of assistance. Finally, the third way will be to make the two clocks [pendules] at first with such skill and accuracy that we can be sure that they will always afterwards keep time together. This is the way of pre-established agreement [consentcmeni], Now put the soul and the body in place of the two clocks. Their agreement [accord] or sympathy will also arise in one of these three ways. The way of in- fluence is that of the common philosophy; but as we cannot conceive material particles or immaterial species or qualities which can pass from one of these substances into the other, we are obliged to give up this opinion. The way of assistance is that of the system of occasional causes ; but I hold that this is to introduce Deus ex machina in a natural and ordinary matter, in which it is reasonable that God should intervene only in the way in which He supports [concourt a] all the other things of nature. Thus there remains only my hypothesis, that is to say, the way of the harmony pre-established by a con- trivance of the Divine foresight, which has from the beginning formed each of these substances in so perfect, so regular and accurate a manner that by merely follow- ing its own laws which were given to it when it came into being, each substance is yet in harmony with the other, just as if there were a mutual influence between them, or as if God were continually putting His hand 334 THIRD EXPLANATION upon them, in addition to His general support [con- currence]. I do not think that I need offer any further proof5 unless I should be required to prove that God is in a position 6 to make use of this contrivance of foresight, of which we have instances even among men, in pro- portion to the skill they have. And supposing that God is able to make use of this means, it is very evident that this is the best way and the most worthy of Him. It is true that I have also other proofs of it 7, but they are deeper and it is unnecessaiy to adduce them here 8. Let me say a word about the dispute between two very clever people, the author of the recently-published Prin- ciples of Physics 9 and the author of the Objections 10 (which appeared in the Journal of August 13 and else wh ere \ because my hypothesis serves to bring these controversies to an end. I do not understand how matter can be 5 It should be observed that Leibniz's argument from analogy proceeds upon the assumption that body and soul, or soul and soul, are in reality quite independent and separate from one another. If this be not admitted his ' proof breaks down : the 'three ways' do not exhaust the possible hypotheses. Leibniz seems rather to have prided himself on emphasizing, by his hypothesis, the difference between body and soul. In the post- script to a letter to Basnage de Beauval (1696), part of which is printed as the Second Edaircissement (E. 134 b; G. iv. 499), Leibniz says: 'You had a suspicion that my explanation would be irre- concilable with the great difference which, in our opinion, there is between mind [esprit] and body. But now you see clearly, Sir, that no one has established their independence more completely than I. For since hitherto we have been obliged to explain their inter-relation [communication] by a kind of miracle, we have con- stantly given occasion to many people to fear that the' distinction between mind and body is not so real as people think, since our reasons for maintaining it are so far-fetched. Now all these scruples 6 The Second Edaircissement reads * is skilful enough.' T The reference is probably to such arguments as those which he afterwards gave in the Monadology. 8 I have omitted two paragraphs dealing with a purely mathe- matical problem. 9 Hartsoeker. See New System, § 6, note 36. 10 Foucher. OF THE NEW SYSTEM 335 conceived as extended and yet without either actual or ideal11 parts; and if it is so, I do not know what is meant by being extended 12. I even hold that matter is essentially an aggregate, and consequently that there are always actual parts. Thus it is by reason, and not merely by the senses, that we judge that it is divided, or rather that it is ultimately nothing but a collection [multitude]. I hold it as true that matter (and even each part of matter) is divided into a greater number of parts than it is possible to imagine. And accordingly I often say that each body, however small it may be, is a world of creatures infinite in number. Thus I do not believe that there are atoms, that is to say, parts of matter which are perfectly hard or of invincible solidity ; while, on the other hand, I as little believe that there is a perfectly fluid matter 1S, and my opinion is that each body is fluid in comparison with more solid bodies and solid in com- parison with the more fluid. I am surprised that it is still said that an equal quantity of motion, in the Car- tesian sense, is always conserved ; for I have proved the opposite, and already excellent mathematicians have admitted it. Nevertheless I do not regard the solidity or consistence of bodies as a primary quality, but as a consequence of motion, and I hope that my Dynamics will show in what this consists, as the understanding of my hypothesis will also serve to remove several diffi- culties which' still engage the attention of philosophers. In fact, I believe I can intelligibly answer all the doubts to which the late M. Bcrnier1* has specially devoted a 11 mentales, i. e. thinkable. 12 The reference is probably to the views of Foucher, who denied that the essence of matter is extension, holding that all our ideas (including those of external objects) are merely modifications of ourselves and that, in order to represent an object, an idea must be like it. See Foucher de Careil, Lettres et Opuscules inedits de Leibniz, Introduction. 13 Hartsoeker's theory was that the ultimate elements of things are perfectly hard atoms in a perfect fluid, the atoms combined forming tangible bodies, while the fluid transmits light, &c. 14 Fran9ois Bernier (d. 1688) was more famous as a traveller 336 THIRD EXPLANATION book ; and those who will think out what I have formerly published will perhaps find that they already have the means of making this answer. than as a philosopher. After travelling in Syria and Egypt, he went to India (where he was physician to Aurungzebe), and afterwards to Cashmir. In Paris he was nicknamed ' the Mogul.' He assisted Boileau in preparing the Mock Decree, given in the hall of Parnassus, in favour of the Masters of Arts, Physicians, and Professors of the University of Stagira, in the land of chimeras, for the support of the doctrine of Aristotle, which by its ridicule killed the serious proposal that the French Parliament should officially condemn the philo- sophy of Descartes. Bernier's principal philosophical works were Abrege de la philosophic de Gassendi (8 vols., 1678) and, by way of supplement to this, Doutes de M. Bernier sur quelques-uns des principaux chapitres de son abrege de la philosophic de Gassendi (7 vols., 1684). The latter is probably the work to which Leibniz refers. There is an English translation of Bernier's Travels in the Mogul Empire (new ed., Constable, 1897). ON THE ULTIMATE ORIGINATION OF THINGS. 1697. PREFATORY NOTE. THIS paper, written in Latin, is dated by Leibniz, November 23> 1697. It may have been int'ended for the Ada Eruditorum ; but it remained unpublished until 1840, when Erdmann in- cluded it in his edition. Leibniz here explains the function of the principle of sufficient reason in his philosophy, expand- ing what he had already said in a paper written about 1685, to which Erdmann give.s the title, De Scientia UniversaU seu Calculo philosophico (see E. 83 b ; G. vii. 200). §§ 36-48 of the Monadology may be regarded as a condensation of the main argument of this Essay On the Ultimate Origination of Things. In the latter part of the Essay we have a vindication of the optimism of Leibniz (that this is the best of all possible worlds), and some of the chief doctrines of the Theodicee are given in outline. The Ultimate Origination of Things is given by E. 147 sqq. ; G. vii. 302 sqq. BESIDES the world or the aggregate of finite things there is a certain unity [unum] which is dominant, not only as the soul is dominant in me or rather as the ego itself is dominant in my body, but also in a much higher sense1. For the dominant unity of the universe not only rules the world but constructs or 2 fashions it. It is higher than the world and, so 'to speak, extramuiidane, and is thus the ultimate reason of things. For the 1 Of. Monadology, §§ 70 and 72, notes in and 115. 2 E. reads ' and.' Z 33$ ON THE ULTIMATE sufficient reason of existence cannot be found either in any particular thing or in the whole aggregate and series of things. Let us suppose that a book of the elements of geometry existed from all eternity and that in succession one copy of it was made from another, it is evident that although we can account for the present book by the book from which it was copied, nevertheless, going back through as many books as we like, we could never reach a complete reason for it, because we can always ask why such books have at all times existed, that is to say, why books at all, and why written in this way. What is true of books is also true of the different states of the world ; for, in spite of certain laws of change, the succeeding state is, in some sort, a copy of that which precedes it. Therefore, to whatever earlier state you go back, you never find in it the complete reason of things, that is to say, the reason why there exists any world and why this world rather than some other. You may indeed suppose the world eternal ; but as you suppose only a succession of states, in none of which do you find the sufficient reason, and as even any number of worlds does not in the least help you to account for them, it is evident that the reason must be sought else- where. For in eternal things, even though there be no cause, there must be a reason 3 which, for permanent things, is necessity itself or essence 4 ; but for the series of changing things, if it be supposed that they succeed one another from all eternity, this reason is, as we shall presently see, the prevailing of inclinations 5 which con- 3 If a thing is eternal, it cannot have a cause in time ; but there must still be some reason (other than a cause in time) for its existence. Cf. Aristotle's airtov (which is wider than our 'cause') and the German Grund. 4 By * permanent things' is meant things that are not contingent, and these, in Leibniz's language, are i possible' things = ' necessary ' th ings = essences. Cf. Monadology, §§ 40 and 43, notes 64 and 67. 5 The sufficient reason of changing or contingent things is not an absolute principle, whose opposite would be self-contradictory, ORIGINATION OF THINGS 339 sist not in necessitating reasons, that is to say, reasons of an absolute and metaphysical necessity, the opposite of which involves a contradiction 6, but in inclining reasons. From this it is manifest that even by sup- posing the eternity of the world, we cannot escape the ultimate extramundane reason of things, that is to say, God7. Accordingly the reasons of the world lie hid in some- thing extramundane, different from the concatenation of states or the series of things, the aggregate of which constitutes the world. And thus we must go beyond the physical or hypothetical necessity, according to which the later things of the world are determined by the earlier, to something which is of absolute or metaphysical necessity8, of which a reason cannot be given. For the present world is necessary physically or hypothetically, but not absolutely or metaphysically. That is to say, the nature of the world being such as it is, it follows that things must happen in it just as they do. There- fore, since the ultimate root of all must be in something which has metaphysical necessity, and since the reason of any existing thing is to be found only in an existing thing, it follows that there must exist one Being which has metaphysical necessity, one Being of whose essence but a superiority of the good or desirable over the bad or un- desirable in the things which come to pass. The balance or preponderance of goodness inclines the will of God (without absolutely necessitating it) to create these contingent things. 6 The word contradictionem seems to have been omitted per incuriam. Neither E. nor G. gives it. 7 Even though the world be taken as eternal, its necessity is not on that account absolute or compelling but merely 'inclining,' and it therefore presupposes some one whose will is 'inclined,' i e. God. 8 E. reads 'something which is absolute or metaphysical ne- cessity.' Absolute or metaphysical necessity is a necessity that is independent of actual things, in contrast with hypothetical (conditional, relative) or physical necessity, which is the necessity arising out of the .natures of actual things, the necessity which a system of ' compossible ' things imposes on its members. Cf. Introduction, Part ii. p. 67. Z 2 340 ON THE ULTIMATE it is to exist9; and thus there must exist something different from that plurality of beings, the world, which as we admitted and showed, has no metaphysical neces- sity10. But to explain more distinctly how from eternal or essential or metaphysical truths there arise temporal, contingent or physical truths, we must first observe that, from the very fact that there exists something rather than nothing,-/ it follows that in possible things, or in possibility or essence itself, there is a certain need of existence or, so to speak, a claim to exist, in a word, that essence of itself tends to existence ^ From this it further follows that all possible things, that is, things expressing essence or possible reality, with equal right tend to existence12 in proportion to the quantity of essence or reality, or in proportion to the degree of per- fection which belongs to them. For perfection is nothing but quantity of essence 13. Hence it is most evident that out of the infinite possible combinations and series of possible things there exists that one through which the greatest amount of essence or possibility is brought into existence. Indeed, there is always in things a principle of determination according to maximum and minimum, so that, for instance, the maximum effect is produced with the minimum out- lay14. And the time, the place, or, in a word, the 9 Cf. Spinoza's distinction between Substance as id quod in se est and Mode as id quod in alio est. Ethics, Part i. deff. 3 and 5. See Monadology, §§36 sqq. 10 For Kant's criticism of the cosmological proof of the existence of God, see Critique of Pure Reason, Transcendental Dialectic, bk. ii. ch. 2, § 2. Fourth Antinomy. " Cf. Monadology, § 40, note 64. 12 Both E. and G. read essentiam, which is manifestly a slip for existentiam. E. corrects the error in his Errata. 13 Cf. Monadology, §§41 and 54. H Outlay or cost is in itself loss or limitation. But if there is to be a world at all, there must be loss or limitation, for if the elements of the world were not in different degrees limited, there would be no variety. All would be one ' splendidly null ' perfec- tion. Yet the world is the best possible world in the sense that it ORIGINATION OF THINGS 341 receptivity or capacity of the world 15 may here be con- sidered as the outlay or ground on which the world is to be built as fittingly [guam commodissime] as possible, while the variety of forms corresponds to the fitness [commoditas] of the building and to the number and elegance of its rooms. The whole matter may be likened to certain games in which all the spaces on a board are to be filled up according to definite rules, so that, unless you make use of some ingenious contrivance, you find yourself in the end kept out of some refractory spaces and compelled to leave empty more spaces than you intended and some which you might otherwise have filled. Yet there is a definite method by which the most complete filling up of the spaces may most easily be accomplished. So if we have to draw a triangle, no other determining condition being given, it will be an equilateral triangle ; and if a line is to be drawn from one point to another, no further condition being assigned, the easiest or shortest way will be chosen. So if once it is given that being is superior to not-being (that is to say, that there is a reason why something should exist rather than nothing 16), or that possibility must pass into actuality, it follows that, though nothing further is determined, there must exist as much as is possible con- sidering the capacity of time and space (that is, of the possible order of existing 17), just as tiles are put together contains the greatest balance of perfection over limitation or of good over evil, i. e. the maximum of advantage at the minimum of cost. In this sense the 'principle of the best,' to which Leibniz constantly refers, is a 'principle of determination according to maximum and minimum.' That the cost should be minimum might be taken as a way of stating the ' law of parsimony.' 15 That is, the natural or essential limits within which the actual world may express an ideal possibility, which has no limits. This limiting 'receptivity or capacity' (which is to the world what the body is to the individual Monad) might be regarded as the passivity or matter of the world, in contrast with its activity or form. 16 Cf. Principles of Nature and of Grace, § 7. 17 i. e. not merely the order which we discover among actual things, but the order which is a condition of possible things 342 ON THE ULTIMATE in such a way that as many as possible may be contained in a given area. Thus it is wonderfully made known to us how in the very origination of things a certain Divine mathematics 1S or metaphysical mechanics is employed and the greatest quantity is brought into existence [lit. the determination of the greatest quantity takes place]. So among all angles the determined [fixed] angle in geometry is the right angle 19, and so also liquids put into heterogeneous media take the form of greatest capacity, that of a sphere. But best of all is the illustration we get in ordinary mechanics, where, when several heavy bodies act against one another, the resultant motion is that which produces the greatest fall on the whole20. For as all possible things by an equal right tend to exist in proportion to their reality, so all weights by an equal right tend to fall in proportion to their gravity ; and as in the case of the latter there is produced a motion which involves the greatest possible fall of the heavy bodies, so in the case of the former there is produced a world in which the greatest number of possible things comes into existence. / And thus we have physical necessity coming from metaphysical necessity ; for although the world is not metaphysically necessary, so that its opposite involves a contradiction or logical absurdity, it is nevertheless physically necessary or so determined that its opposite involves imperfection or moral absurdity. And as possi- bility is the principle of essence, so perfection or degree coming into existence. Only compossible essences can give rise to co-existing phenomena, and time and space are the order of co-existence of these phenomena. See Introduction, Part iii. p. 102. is < \\nhen God calculates and employs thought, the world is made.' De connexione inter res et verba (1677) (E. 77 a ; G. vii. 191). The phrase was written by Leibniz on the margin of the MS. and may accordingly be of later date. 19 The right angle is always 90° ; but an acute or an obtuse angle is variable in size. The right angle is thus l fixed ' or ' determined, ' and the right angle is the greatest angle at which one line can meet another. 20 The suggestion is of some such arrangement as we have in a system of pulleys. ORIGINATION OF THINGS 343 of essence (through which more things are compossible the greater it is) is the principle of existence. Whence at the same time it is manifest how the Author of the world is free, although He does all things determinately, for He acts from a principle of wisdom or perfection. Indifference springs from ignorance, and the wiser a man is the more is he determined towards that which is most perfect 21. ~T3ul, you will* say, however beautiful may seem this comparison of a certain metaphysical determining me- chanism with the physical mechanism of heavy bodies, it nevertheless fails in this respect that heavy bodies really exist and act, but possibilities or essences anterior to existence or apart from it are imaginary or fictitious and therefore no reason22 of existence is to be sought in them. I reply that neither these essences nor what are called eternal truths regarding these essences are ficti- tious, but that they exist in a certain region (if I may so call it) of ideas, that is to say, in God Himself, the source of all essence and of the existence of other things. That this is not a mere gratuitous assertion of mine is shown by the existence of the actual series of things. For since the reason of the series is not to be found in itself, as has been shown above, but is to be sought in metaphysical necessities or eternal truths, and since existing things can come only from existing things, as we have already remarked, eternal truths must have existence in some absolutely or 23 metaphysically necessary subject, that is, in God, through whom these things which would other- wise be imaginary are (to use a barbarous but expressive word) realized 24. ^ And indeed we actually find that all things in the 21 Cf. Introduction, Part iii. p. 145. 22 Or ' ground.' 23 E. reads ' and.' 24 That is to say, God gives them a certain reality or existence in His understanding, as distinct from existence in the actual world, which belongs to contingent things. Cf. Monadology, §§ 43, 44, 46 and 47, note 75. 344 ON THE ULTIMATE / world take place in accordance with the laws, not only geometrical but also metaphysical, of eternal truths, that is, not only in accordance with material necessities but also in accordance with formal reasons25. And this is not only true in general as regards the reason (which we have just explained) -why a world exists rather than not, and why it exists thus rather than otherwise (a reason which is to be found only in the tendency of possible things to exist) ; but also when we come down to par- ticular things we see that metaphysical laws of cause, power, activity, are present in a wonderful way through- out the whole of nature, and that they are even superior to the purely geometrical laws of matter, as to my great astonishment I found when I was explaining the laws of motion, so that, as I have elsewhere more fully ex- plained 26, I was ultimately compelled to give up the law of the geometrical composition of forces [conatus] which I had maintained in my youth when I had more belief in the material view. / Accordingly we have the ultimate reason of the reality both of essences and of existences in one Being who is necessarily greater, higher, and older [anterius] than the world itself, since through Him not only the existing things which the world contains but also possible things have reality. But this ultimate reason can be found only in one source on account of the inter-connexion of all these things27. But it is manifest that from this source existing things continually come forth [promanare], that they are being and have been produced by it, since it does not appear why one state of the world rather than another, the state of yesterday rather than that of to-day, should flow from it28. It is also manifest how 25 E. reads 'necessities' instead of 'reasons/ 26 See Appendix I, p. 351. 27 That is to say, the actual system of things is one and therefore its source is one. Cf. Monadology, § 39. 28 The reference is not quite clear. Janet translates 'from the world itself.' Kirchmann translates 'from this source.' On Janet's ORIGINATION OF THINGS 345 God acts not only physically but also freely, how not only the efficient but also the final cause of things is in Him, and how He manifests not only His greatness and power in the mechanism of the world as already con- structed, but also His wisdom and goodness in the constructing of it 29. And lest any one should think that we are here con- founding moral perfection or goodness with metaphysical perfection or greatness and, allowing the latter, should deny the former, it is to be observed that it follows from what has been said not only that the world is most perfect physically, or, if you prefer it, metaphysically, that is to say, that that series of things has come into existence in which the greatest amount of reality is actually manifested, but also that the world is most perfect morally because genuine moral perfection is phy- sical 30 perfection in minds [mentes] themselves. Where- fore the world is not only the most admirable mechanism, but it is also, in so far as it is made up of minds [mentes], the best commonwealth, through which there is be- stowed upon minds the greatest possible happiness or joy, in which their physical perfection consists31. interpretation, the passage would mean that all the states of the world must come from God, in whose nature is to be found the sufficient reason of all and of each, and not from the world itself, which cannot supply the sufficient reason of any. On Kirchmann's interpretation, the meaning would be that each state of the world comes from God by a ' continual creation,' because there is no reason why God should create one state rather than another. Both inter- pretations are possible ; but Janet's seems the more natural. 29 Cf. Monadology, §§ 47, 48, 55. so i Physical ' here means ' natural ' or ' according to the specific nature (Averts] of the thing ' in contrast with ' metaphysical ' in the sense of ' absolute, independent of the specific nature of the thing.' Thus (cf. supra} l the world is most perfect physically ' means that its individual members or elements are as perfect as the nature of each allows, while ' the world is most perfect metaphysically ' means that the world as a whole is the most perfect possible. So also ' genuine moral perfection is physical perfection in minds them- selves ' means that the specific natural perfection of mind is moral perfection. 31 Cf. Monadology, §§86 sqq. 'Felicity is to persons what per- fection is to beings.' Paper without a title (1686) (G. iv. 462). 346 ON THE ULTIMATE But, you will say, we find that the opposite of this takes place in the world, for veiy often the best people suffer the worst things, and those who are innocent, both animals and men, are afflicted and put to death even with torture ; and indeed the world, especially if we consider the government of the human race, seems rather a confused chaos than anything directed by a supreme wisdom. So, I confess, it seems at a first glance, but when we look at it more closely the opposite conclusion manifestly follows a priori from those very considerations which have been adduced, the conclusion, namely, that the highest possible perfection of all things, and therefore of all minds, is brought about. — And indeed, as the lawyers say, it is not proper to judge unless we have examined the whole law. We know a very small part of eternity which is immeasure- able in its extent ; for what a little thing is the record of a few thousand years, which history transmits to us ! Nevertheless, from so slight an experience we rashly judge regarding the immeasureable and eternal, like men who, having been born and brought up in prison or, perhaps, in the subterranean salt-mines of the Sarma- tians32, should think that there is no oth^r light in the " The reference is probably to some of the salt-mines in or near the Carpathians, which are the richest in Europe. The most famous salt-mines in the world are at Wielicza, near Cracow in Galicia (which in Leibniz's time was still part of the kingdom of Poland). They have been worked for about 600 years, and many of the workers live permanently underground, there being streets and houses and, in short, something like a village in the lower levels. In Jeremy Collier's Dictionary, published towards the end of the seventeenth century, the famous salt-mines are said to be those of Eperies, in northern Hungary, on the other side of the Carpathians from Cracow. Sarmatia is a very vague word. Ac- cording to Ptolemy it included all the eastern European plain from the Vistula and the Dniester to the Volga. In any case it included the district of the salt-mines referred to. Leibniz elsewhere seems to identify Sarmatian with Slavonic speech. (Nouveaux Essais, iii. 2, § i ; E. 299 b ; G. v. 259, 260.) In English verse, Sarmatia is often used as synonymous with Poland, e. g. ' Sarmatia fell, un- wept, without a crime ' (Campbell, Pkasures of Hope, Part i. line 376 ; see also 1. 407). ORIGINATION OF THINGS 347 world than that of the feeble lamp which hardly suffices to direct their steps. If you look at a very beautiful picture, having covered up the whole of it except a very small part, what will it present to your sight, however thoroughly you examine it (nay, so much the more, the more closely you inspect it), but a confused mass of colours laid on without selection and without art ? Yet if you remove the covering and look at the whole picture from the right point of view, you will see that what appeared to have been carelessly daubed on the canvas was really done by the painter with very great art33. The experience of the eyes in painting corresponds to that of the ears in music. Eminent composers very often mingle discords with harmonies so as to stimulate and, as it were, to prick the hearer, who becomes anxious as to what is going to happen, and is so much the more pleased when presently all is restored to order ; just as we take pleasure in small dangers or risks of mishap, merely from the consciousness of our power or our luck or from a desire to make a display of them ; or, again, as we delight in the show of danger that is connected with performances on the tight-rope or sword-dancing (sauts perilleux)3*, and we ourselves in jest half let go a little boy, as if about to throw him from us, like the ape which carried Christiern, King of Denmark35, while still an infant in swaddling-clothes, to the top of the roof, and then, as in jest, relieved the anxiety of every one by bringing him safely back to his cradle. On the same principle sweet things become insipid if we eat nothing else ; sharp, tart, and even bitter things must be com- bined with them, so as to stimulate the taste. He 33 A most interesting variant of this illustration occurs in Bosanquet's Essentials of Logic, pp. 55 sqq. 34 Leibniz gives the French phrase to explain his Latin. 35 Probably Christiern or Christian V (1646-1699), the first hereditary (not elected) King of Denmark, who was reigning at the time when Leibniz wrote. In the text he is called Christiernus, Christiern or Kristiern being the Danish form of the name. 3-j 8 OX THE ULTIMATE who has not tasted bitter things does not deserve sweet things and, indeed, will not appreciate them. This is the very law of enjoyment, that pleasure does not have an even tenor, for this begets loathing and makes us dull, not happy36. But as to our saying that a part may be disturbed without destroying harmony in the whole, this must not be understood as meaning that no account is taken of the parts or that it is enough for the world as a whole to be perfect, although it may be that the human race is wretched, and that there is in the universe no regard for justice and no care for us, as is the opinion of some whose judgment regarding the totality of things is not quite just. For it is to be observed that, as in a thoroughly well-constituted commonwealth care is taken, as far as may be, for the good of individuals, so the universe will not be sufficiently perfect unless the interests of individuals are attended to, while the universal harmony is preserved37. And for this no 36 'To have a thousand well-bound Virgils in your library, always to sing airs from the opera of Cadmus and Hermioiie, to break all your porcelain that you might have nothing but cups of gold, to have diamonds alone for buttons, to eat nothing but partridges, to drink only Hungarian or Shiras wine — would you call that reason?' Theodicee, § 124 (E. 539 b ; G. vi. 179). Cf. Principles of Nature and of Grace, § 18 ; also Bacon, De Augmenlis, iii. i. 37 Cf. Theodicee, § 118 (E. 535 a ; G. vi. 169): 'No substance is absolutely contemptible or precious in the sight of God. ... It is certain that God gives more importance to a man than to a lion ; yet I do not know if we can be certain that God prefers one man to the whole species of lions in all respects. But even if it were so, it would not follow that the interest of a certain number of men should prevail in face of a general disorder, extending to an infinite number of created things. This opinion would be a relic of the old maxim, now quite out of repute,, that everything happens solely on man's account.' Cf. Meditation sur la notion commune de la justice (Mollat, p. 63) : 'There are people who think that we are of too little consequence, in the sight of an infinite God, for Him to have any care for us : we are supposed to be in relation to God what the worms, which we crush without thinking about it, are in relation to us. But this is to suppose that God is like a man and cannot think of everything. Just because God is infinite, He does things without labour by a kind of consequence of His will,- as it is a consequence of my will and that of my friend that we are in ORIGINATION OF THINGS 349 better standard could be set up than the very law of justice which declares that each should participate in the perfection of the universe and in a happiness of his own in proportion to his own virtue and to the degree in which his will has regard to the common good ; and by this is fulfilled that which we call charity and the love of God, in which alone, in the opinion of wise theologians, consists the force and power even of the Christian religion 38. Nor ought it to appear wonderful that so great a place should be given to minds in the universe, since they most closely resemble the image of the Supreme Author ; they are related to Him, not (like other things) as machines to their constructor, but as citizens to their prince ; they are to last as long as the universe itself, and in a manner they express and concentrate the whole in themselves, so that it may be said that minds are whole parts [paries totalesY9- But as to the special question of the afflictions of good men, it is to be held as certain that these afflictions have as their result the greater good of those who are afflicted, and this is true not only theologically but also naturally [physice], as the grain cast into the earth suffers before it bears fruit. And in general it may be said that afflictions are for the time evil but in the end good, since they are short ways to greater perfection. So in physics, liquids which ferment slowly take also a longer time to purify, agreement, no new action being required to produce our agree- ment, beyond the resolve which each of us has made. Now if the human race and even the smallest thing were not well governed, the universe itself would not be well governed, for the whole consists in its parts/ i8 Of. Pope, Essay on Man, Fourth Epistle, lines 327 sqq. Nature, says Pope, connects 'Man's greatest virtue with his greatest bliss. Self-love thus push'd to social, to divine, Gives thee to make thy neighbour's blessing thine. Happier as kinder, in whate'er degree And height of bliss but height of charity. 39 See Introduction, Part ii. p. 31. 350 ULTIMATE ORIGINATION OF THINGS while those which undergo a greater agitation throw off certain of their ingredients with greater force, and are thus more quickly rectified. And this is what you might call going back in order that you may put more force into your leap forward (qu'on recede pour mieux sauter™}. Wherefore these things are to be regarded not only as agreeable and comforting, but also as most true. And in general I think there is nothing more true than happiness, and nothing more happy and pleasant than truth. Further, to realize in its completeness the universal beauty and perfection of the works of God, we must recognize a certain perpetual and very free progress of the whole universe, such that it is always going forward to greater improvement [cuttus]. So even now a great part of our earth has received cultivation [culturd] and will receive it more and more. And although it is true that sometimes certain parts of it grow wild again, or again suffer destruction or degeneration, yet this is to be understood in the way in which affliction was explained above, that is to say, that this very destruction and degeneration leads to some greater end, so that somehow we profit by the loss itself41. And to the possible objection that, if this were so, the world ought long ago to have become a paradise, there is a ready answer. Although many substances have 40 Cf. Principles of Nature and of Grace, § 12, note 51. 41 Cf. Lettre a la Princesse Sophie (1706) (G. vii. 568) : 'And as there is reason to think that the universe itself develops from more to more and that all tends to some end, since all comes from an Author whose wisdom is perfect, we may similarly believe that souls, which last as long as the universe, go also from better to better, at least naturally [physiquement] and that their perfections go on increasing, although most often this takes place imperceptibly and sometimes after great circuits backward.' See also Lettre a Bourguet (1716) (G. iii. 589) : 'Although the universe has always been equally perfect ' [i. e. each momentary state of the universe equally perfect with every other] ' it will never be supremely perfect ; for it always changes and gains new perfections, though it loses old ones.' APPENDIX I 351 already attained a great perfection, yet on account of the infinite divisibility of the continuous, there always remain in the abyss of things slumbering parts which have yet to be awakened, to grow in size and worth, and, in a word, to advance to a more perfect state [ad meliorem cultum\. And hence no end of progress is ever reached. APPENDIX I. THE GROWTH OF LEIBNIZ^ THEORIES REGARDING FORCE AND MOTION. IN the second of two dialogues, entitled Phoranomus sen de Potentia et Legibus Naturae (1689), Leibniz gives an account of the progress of his views regarding dynamics and physics. What follows is a portion of this account, combined with part of a similar statement in the Specimen Dynamicum. ' When first I escaped from the prickly thorn-brakes of the schools into the more pleasant fields of later philosophy, I was greatly taken with that fascinating ease of understanding, in which I saw a lucid imagination comprehending all the things which formerly were wrapped in dark notions And after long and careful deliberation I at length rejected the " forms " and " qualities " of material things, and reduced all things to purely mathematical principles ; but since I was not yet versed in geometry, I was convinced that a continuum consists of points and that a very slow motion is broken by little bits of rest, and I was inclined to other doctrines of this kind, which commend themselves to those who seek to comprehend all things with the imagination and who do not notice the infinite which is everywhere latent in things. But although, when I became a geometrician, I put off these opinions, there yet remained for a while atoms and the void, as relics of a state of mind that was in revolt against the idea of the infinite ; for although I granted that every continuum can in thought be divided ad infinitum, yet I did not really accept the view that in things there are innumerable parts which follow from motion in the plenum. At last, not only was I freed from this scruple, but also I began to recognize something deeper in bodies, which 352 APPENDIX I could not be comprehended by the imagination. . . . This ought not to seem wonderful, for it is the nature of foundations to be humble, but if they are securely laid, great masses arise upon them. Accordingly, when I as yet acknowledged the jurisdiction of imagination alone in regard to material things, I was of opinion that any natural inertia in bodies was unintelligible, and that a body at rest in vacuo or in a free space must receive the velocity of another, however small that other might be ; and that this does not actually happen in our experience I attributed to the system established by the wisdom of the Supreme Author of things, in which all things are ruled by the most just laws. Nor indeed did I doubt that the origin of the system might be rationally thought out on mechanical principles from those very laws of natural bodies, which explain occurrences by the composition of motions, such as I expounded regarding several cases in a treatise which I published when a young man.' Phoranomus, see Arch. f. Gesch. d. Phil. i. 577. 'When I was a young man and, at that time, following Democritus and his adherents in this matter, Gassendi and Descartes, I regarded the nature of body as consisting in mere inert mass, I issued a treatise with the title Hypothesis Physica, in which I expounded a theory of motion both abstract (inde- pendent of the system of things) and concrete (as it appears in the system of things), which I see has pleased many distinguished men better than its moderate worth deserved. In this treatise I maintained that, supposing my view of the nature of body to be right, every impinging body gives its impulse [conatus] to the body on which it impinges or which is directly in its way, as such. For when the impact takes place, the body impinged upon endeavours to move forward and thus to go away, and (since, as I then thought, body is indifferent to motion or rest) this endeavour [effort, conatus] must have its full effect in the body impinged upon, unless it is hindered by an opposite effort, and even if it is so hindered, since these different efforts must be compounded together. Accordingly it was manifest that no cause can be given why the impinging body should not achieve the effect towards which it tends or why the body impinged upon should not receive the whole impulse [conatus] of the impinging body, and therefore the motion of the body impinged upon is compounded of its own original impulse and the new or foreign impulse it has received. Whence I further showed that if in body there APPENDIX I 353 were recognized only mathematical notions, magnitude, figure, place, and their changes or their tendency [conatus] to change at the very moment of impact, and no account were taken of metaphysical notions, namely, of moving power [potentia] in the form, and of inertia (or resistance to motion) in the matter [of the body], and if it were thus necessary that the result of the impact should be determined by a purely geometrical composition of forces [conatus], as we have explained: then it ought to follow that the impulse of the impinging body, however small that body may be, is communicated to the whole of the body impinged upon, however large it may be, and thus the very largest body at rest is moved away by an impinging body, however small, without any retarding of the latter, since matter, thus understood, is not repugnant but rather indifferent to motion. Hence it would not be more difficult to move ^ a large body at rest than a small one, and therefore there >w would be action without reaction, and no estimate of power ) could be made, since anything might be accomplished by / anything. . . . But afterwards, having considered the whole / matter more profoundly, I saw in what the systematic explana- x. . tion of things ' [i. e. the explanation of things as they actually ^ are] ' should consist, and I observed that my former hypothesis regarding the nature of body was not complete, and that this as well as other arguments proved that body must be regarded as having, in addition to magnitude and impenetrability, something from which arises the consideration of forces [vires], the metaphysical laws of which, when combined with the laws of extension, give rise to those very laws of motion which I had called systematic. . . .' Specimen Dynamicum, &c. (1695) (G. Math. vi. 240). ' I am of opinion that the mechanical principles and reasons of the laws of motion do themselves arise not from the necessity of matter, but from some higher principle than imagination, and one independent of mathematics. . . . Besides I began to have considerable doubts as to the nature of motion. For when formerly I regarded space as an immovable real place, possessing extension alone, I had been able to define absolute motion as change of this real space. But gradually I began to doubt whether there is in nature such an entity as is called space ;> whence it followed that a doubt might arise about absolute motion. Certainly Aristotle had said that place is notl>:ng but the surface of what surrounds us A a 354 APPENDIX I [superficies ambientis]1, and Descartes, following him, had defined motion (that is, change of place) as change of neighbourhood \mutatio mciniae]. Whence it seemed to follow that that which is real and absolute in motion consists not in what is purely 'mathematical, such as change of neighbourhood or situation, but in motive force [potentia matrix] itself; and if there is none of this, then there is no absolute and real motion. . . . Accordingly I found no other 'Ariadne thread to lead me out of this labyrinth than the calculation of forces [potentiae], assuming this metaphysical principle, "That the total effect is always equal to its complete cause" \Quod effectus integer sit semper aequalis causae suae plenae]. When I discovered that this agrees perfectly with experience and satisfies all doubts, I was more confirmed in my opinion that the causes of things are not, so to speak, senseless [surdus] and purely mathematical, like the concourse of atoms or the blind force of nature, but proceed from an intelligence which employs metaphysical reasons.' Phoranomus, see Arch. f. Gesch. d. Phil. i. 577. In the first of these dialogues (Phoranomus, &c.) Leibniz says: 'As in geometiy and numbers, through the principle of the equality of the whole to all its parts, geometry is brought within the ecope of an analytical calculus, so in mechanics, through the principle of the equality of the eifect to all its causes or of the cause to all its effects, we obtain certain equations, as it were, and a kind of algebraic mechanics.' tloc. cit. p. 576. Cf. Introduction to this book, Part iii. p. 107 note. 1 Phys. A. 4. 212* 20. NEW ESSAYS ON THE HUMAN1 UNDER- STANDING. 1704. BY THE AUTHOR OF THE SYSTEM OF PRE- ESTABLISHED HARMONY. PREFATORY NOTE. THE New Essays contain the fullest statement of Leibniz's appreciation and criticism of Locke. Leibniz became ac- quainted with the main outline of Locke's Essay, before it was actually published in English, by means of an abstract of the book, prepared by Locke, translated into French and published in Le Clerc's Bibliofheque Universelle (1688), vol. 8, pp. 49 sqq. When in 1690 the Essay itself was published Leibniz read it, making notes as he went, and his criticisms were expressed in various short papers, some of which were transmitted to Locke through Thomas Burnet of Kemnay. Locke, however, seems rather to have disparaged Leibniz's criticisms and he did not count them worthy of a reply. Meanwhile Locke's Essay passed through several editions, and in 1700 Coste's French translation of it was published. This enabled Leibniz, whose knowledge of English was somewhat imperfect, to make a thorough study of the Essay, and after writing some papers on special parts of it, he set himself to the task of preparing the elaborate exposition and criticism of the Essay which was after- wards published as the New Essays. The book was written somewhat hurriedly and discontinuously, during scraps of 1 G., with over-accuracy, omits ' human,' which Leibniz cannot deliberately have intended to omit, for he includes it in the titles of the first three books of the New Essays. A a 2 35^ NEW ESSAYS leisure time. Accordingly Leibniz, in view of publication, submitted his work to Hugony and Barbeyrac (the great jurist), who revised a considerable portion of it, including the Intro- duction, and made numerous changes in its expression. Meanwhile a new edition of Coste's translation, revised and corrected by Locke himself, was promised, and Leibniz was strongly advised by Coste to delay publication until after he had seen this new edition. Locke died in the end of 1 704, and Leibniz, understanding that he had made considerable changes in his .opinions, felt that it was now of little use to publish his own criticism. Accordingly the New Essays remained in manuscript until 1765, when they were published by Raspe. He printed the text in the form which it had finally assumed after the correction and revision of Hugony, Barbeyrac and Leibniz himself. Erclmann (E. 194 sqq.) follows this text. Gerhardt (G. v. 39 sqq.), however, has thought it better to reconstruct the original text, by going behind the corrections, on the ground that, while these corrections often improve the French style of the original, they do not always so well express Leibniz's thought. Boutroux, approving the course taken by Gerhardt, has in various points corrected the text made by that editor. My translation is made from Boutroux's text. Such variations as involve a change in translation are mentioned in foot-notes. In the Introduction to the New Essays (which was written later than the rest of the book), Leibniz summarizes the main points regarding which he differs from Locke, while he characteristically suggests that, after all, the differences between his view and that of Locke are not altogether in- surmountable. After some prefatory sentences, the Intro- duction deals in the first place (a) with the question whether (as Locke held) the mind is tabula rasa or whether (as Leibniz thought) there are innate ideas, necessary truths, including the question whether or not all our knowledge comes from the senses (pp. 357-367). (V) This leads naturally to the question whether (as Locke seems to say) there is nothing in our mind of which we are not actually conscious or whether (as Leibniz maintains) we have unconscious perceptions (pp. 367-385). Leibniz here connects his psychology with his metaphysics by showing how the petites perceptions throw light upon the pre- established harmony, the law of continuity, the identity of NEW ESSAYS 357 indiscernibles and the indestructibility of souls, as well as their inseparability from bodies, (c) The next question con- sidered is that of atoms and the void (in which Locke believes) as against a plenum (Leibniz's view) (pp. 385 sqq.). (d) References to the criticism of Locke by Stillingfleet lead to a consideration of the question whether matter can think, Locke maintaining the possibility of this, while Stillingfleet and Leibniz deny it (PP- 39° sqq.-)' This gives occasion to Leibniz to draw a distinction between .the physical or real genus of a thing and its logical or ideal genus (p. 394), and in the remainder of the Introduction he applies this distinction, maintaining that as matter and soul are heterogeneous (i.e. not of the same physical or real genus), thinking, which is a mode of soul, cannot be a mode of matter, except by miracle, and that accordingly, if Locke's contention were true, we should have to adopt a philosophy of unintelligible qualities or faculties, which would be even worse than the Scholastic theories of ' occult ' qualities or faculties, so justly derided by later thinkers. INTRODUCTION. As the Essay on the Understanding 2, by an illustrious Englishman, is one of the best and most highly esteemed works of the present time, I have resolved to make some remarks upon it, because, having for a long time given considerable attention to the same subject and to most of the matters with which the essay deals, I have thought that this would be a good occasion for publishing some of my opinions under the title of New Essays on the Understanding, in the hope that my thoughts will obtain a favourable3 reception through appearing in such good company. I have hoped also to be able to profit by the work of another, not only in the way of lessening my own work (as in fact it is less trouble to follow the thread of a good author than to work on entirely un- trodden ground) 4, but also in the way of adding some- 2 E. reads 'human understanding.' 3 E. reads ' more favourable.' 4 E. omits the clause in brackets. 358 NEW ESSAYS thing to what he has given us, which is always easier than making an independent beginning5. For I think I have removed some difficulties which he left entirely alone. Thus his reputation is helpful to me ; and besides, being disposed to do justice and very far from wishing to lessen the esteem in which his work is held, I would increase his reputation, if my approval have any weight 6. It is true that I often differ from him in opinion ; but, far from 7 denying the worth of famous writers, we bear witness to it by making known in what respect and for what reasons we differ from their opinion, when we think it necessary to prevent their authority from pre- vailing against reason on some important points 8 ; and besides, in replying to such excellent men, we make it easier for the truth to be accepted, and it is to be supposed that it is principally for truth that they are working. In fact, although the author of the Essay says a thousand fine things of which I cordially approve, our systems greatly differ. His has more relation to Aristotle and mine to Plato 9, although in many things both of us have 5 E. omits 'always' and adds (after 'beginning'), 'and working on entirely untrodden ground.' 6 E. omits from ' For I think ' to ' any weight.' 7 E. reads 'denying on that account the worth of this famous writer, I do him justice,' &c. 8 E. omits the remainder of the sentence, from this point. 9 The main principles of Leibniz's philosophy are really much more akin to the philosophy of Aristotle than to the doctrines which are peculiar to Plato. But, as regards Aristotle, Leibniz is here thinking of that side of his philosophy which led the Scholastics to attribute to him the saying, NihU est in intelledu quod non prius fuerit in sensu. (Cf. Duns Scotus, Super Universalibus Porphyrii, Question 3 : Itta propositio Aristotelis, nihil est in intelledu quin prius fuerit in sensu. . . .) This phrase does not occur in any of Aristotle's writings ; but it serves as a fair enough analysis of several passages in the Posterior Analytics, in which firi(TTrjfj.T) is traced to aiaOijais, though other passages supplement this by bringing in the work of vovs. (See especially Anal. Post. ii. 19, and Eth. vi. 3, § 3.) The view that the soul is a tabula rasa is suggested by the passage : NEW ESSAYS 359 departed from the doctrine of these two ancient writers. He is more popular, and I for my part am sometimes compelled to be a little more acroamatic^ and abstract, which is not of advantage to me, especially when a living language is used. But I think that by introducing two speakers, one of whom expounds opinions taken from this author's Essay, while the other adds my observations, I show the relation between us in a way that will be more satisfactory to the reader than if I had put down mere remarks, the reading of which would have been constantly interrupted by the necessity of turning to his book in order to understand mine. Nevertheless it will be well also to compare our writings sometimes, and not to judge of his opinions except from his own work, although I have usually retained his expressions. It is true that owing to the limitations involved in following the thread of another person's argument and making remarks upon it, I have been unable even to think of achieving the graceful turns of which dialogue is sus- ceptible ; but I hope that the matter will make up for the defects of the style. 8vva.fj.ei TTWS fffTi ra vorjTO. 6 vovs, a\\' fVT(\f)^eiq. ovSev, irplf av vorj. 8(t 8' OVTQJS (aOTTCp kv Ypa/^uaTe/oj <£ ftrjOev vTrdpxd fVTf\€^ia yfypa/j.fj,evov (De Anima, iii. 4. 429** 30). Cf. note 12, infra. In regard to Plato, on the other handj Leibniz is probably thinking mainly of the Platonic theory of reminiscence, according to which our knowledge of realities, in so far as we can attain to it, is a recollection or restoration of knowledge possessed by the soul in a previous state, so that necessary and eternal truths are, in a sense, innate in us. On the whole matter cf. Nolen, Quid Leibnizius Aristoteli debuerit, and Trendelenburg, Hist. Beitrage, vol. ii. 10 i. e. esoteric. See Aulus G-ellius, Nodes Atticae, xx. 5 (quoted by Eitter and Preller, Hist. Phil. Graec. § 298), where a distinction is drawn between the exoteric and the ' acroatic ' writings of Aristotle. Leibniz himself defines the word : ' The acroamatic way of philoso- phizing is that in which all things are demonstrated, the exoteric is that in which certain things are said without demonstra- tion, and yet are confirmed by the consistency they have with various other things and by probable [topicae] reasons (or even reasons that might demonstrate, but are put forward only aa 360 NEW ESSAYS The differences between us have regard to subjects u of some importance. There is the question whether the soul, in itself, is entirely empty, like a writing- tablet on which nothing has yet been written (tabula rasa), (which is the opinion of Aristotle 12 and of the author of the Essay), and whether everything that is inscribed upon it comes solely from the senses and experience ; or whether the soul originally contains the principles13 of several notions and doctrines, which are merely roused on certain occasions by external objects, as I hold along with Plato and even with the Schoolmen, and with all those who interpret in this sense the passage of St. Paul (Eomans, ii. 15), in which he shows that the law of God is written in men's hearts. The Stoics called these principles H 15, that is, fundamental assumptions or what probable), and are illustrated by instances and similar cases.' De stilo philosophico Nisolii (1670) (E. 63 a ; G. iv. 146). 11 E. reads ' objects.' 12 Cf. note 9. Aristotle's meaning, however, is very different from that of Locke. 6 vovs is not the ' soul,' but reason as opposed to sense. And there is a vovs diraOrjs. The context of the passage in which vovs is compared to the writing-tablet shows that Aristotle merely meant to protest against the view that reason has certain complete l ready-made ' ideas, apart from all sense- experience. But this is quite consistent with holding that there are in reason potential or virtual forms or ideas. Even the clean writing-tablet is at least a writing-tablet and not a sheet of water on which nothing can be written. Cf. De Anima, iii. 4. 429* 27 : KOL ev 5r) ol \eyovT€S rr\v ^i/x^i/ fivai TOTTOV fiSuv, Tr\r]v on ovre o\rj a\\' rj voijriKr], ovTf Ij/Te\«x€"? oAAa owdfi€i TO, 6?8?7. Cf. Analytica Post. ii. 19, 99b 20 sqq. 13 apxai, grounds or sources. 14 E. reads ' common notions ' after ' principles.' 15 The original has prolepses. The Stoic irp6\r}\f>is, however, was not an anticipation prior to, or presupposed by, all experience, but the common image resulting from a series of sense-impressions, which leads us to expect other similar impressions. The distin- guishing characteristic of the npo\Tj^fis is that they arise tyvtriKtas (naturally), and are not deliberately constructed by us. Thus Diogenes Laertius, vii. 54 : can 8' 77 TrpoA.^? (vvoia vffiKt) ruv Ka0u\ov. Cf. Placita, iv. ii, quoted by Hitter and Preller, Hist. Phil. Graec. § 393, in which the Stoics are represented as holding a view NEW ESSAYS 361 we take for granted beforehand. Mathematicians call them common notions (KOLVOL ewowu)16. Modern philo- sophers give them other excellent names ; and, in particular, Julius Scaliger17 named them semina aeter- nitatis item zopyra18, as much as to say, living fires, flashes of light [traits lumineux] 19, hidden within us but appearing at the instance of the senses, like the sparks which come from the steel when it strikes the flint. And not without reason it is thought that these flashes [eclats] indicate something divine and eternal, which appears above all in necessary truths. Hence there arises another question, whether all truths are dependent on experience, that is, on induction and instances ; or whether there are some which have yet another founda- tion. For if some events can be foreseen before we have made any trial of them, it is manifest that we contribute much more akin to that of Locke than to that of Leibniz : ot (paffiv orav fevvrjOf) 6 dvOpcairos, *x6£ T° fftfuoviicbv pepos TTJS wffTTfp xapTyv cvfpyov fh airoypcHprjv' els TOVTO fj.iav tKaarrjv TUV evvoiwv fv 'superadds to the essence of matter what qualities and perfections He pleases : to some parts mere motion, but to plants vegetation, and to animals feeling [sentiment]. Those who agree with me so far exclaim 155 rpne pOin£ gjniply is that, no real thing can have two or more conflicting attributes, though it may at different times have modifica- tions which in themselves are conflicting. Nevertheless attributes which, in a real thing, would be impossible because conflicting, may abstractly or 'ideally' be comprehended under the same concept or in the same class, on the ground that there is an essential (not merely accidental) community between them. They are thus species of a logical genus. Modifications, on the other hand, are more or less accidental variations of some real thing, which is the bond of union between them. They are thus species of a real genus. Ultimately, perhaps, the modifications may^Eum out to be species of a logical genus (it is probable that they are so in the mind of God) ; but, for us, an infinite analysis would be needed to show this."-~ 156 TMS ' filiation ' as a whole is, of course, an arrangement of logical genera and species. 187 * Matter ' here is equivalent to ' real genus/ 158 wof-fa (e(L 1823), vol. iv. p. 460 ; Bonn's ed., vol. ii. p. 390. In translating this passage I have used Locke's words as much as possible. S96 NEW ESSAYS against me when I go a step further and say, God may give to matter thought, reason and volition, as if that were to destroy the essence of matter. But to make good this assertion they say that thought and reason are not included in the essence of matter ; which proves nothing, for motion and life are just as little included in it. They also urge that we cannot conceive how matter can think ; but our conception is not the measure of God's omnipotency 15V He afterwards takes as an instance the attraction of matter, on p. 991CO, but especially on p. 408 161, where he speaks of the gravitation of matter towards matter, attributed to Mr. Newton (in words which I have quoted above), declaring that we can never conceive the * how ' of it. This is practically to go back toj>ccult qualities 162, nay more, to inexplicable qualities. He adds (p. 401) 163 that nothing is more calculated to favour scepticism than to deny what one does not under- stand, and (p. 402 )163 that we do not conceive how even the soul thinks. He thinks (p. 403 )J68 that as the two substances, material and immaterial, can be conceived in their bare essence without any activity, it is in the power of God to give to the one or the other the power of thinking. And he endeavours to take advantage of the admission of his opponent, who attributed sense [sentiment] to the lower animals, but did not attribute to them any immaterial substance l6*. He maintains that liberty and self-consciousness [la consciosite] (p. 408 )It6, and the power of making abstractions (p. 40p)16& can 159 Cf. Essay, Eraser's ed., vol. ii. p. 240 note. 160 All the. texts give '99,' which seems to be a slip for '399.' Works (ed. 1823), iv. 463 sqq. ; Bohn's ed., ii. 392 sqq. 161 Works (ed. 1823), iv. 467 ; Bohn's ed., ii. 395. 162 The qualitates occultae of the Scholastics. See Introduction, Part iv. p. 156. 163 Works (ed. 1823), iv. 463; Bohn's ed., ii. 392. Cf. Essay, Eraser's ed., vol. ii. p. 194 note. 16* Works, iv. 466 ; Bohn's ed., ii. 394. 165 Works, iv. 468 ; Bohn's ed., ii. 395. OF THK I UNIVERSITY NEW ESSAYS \397 be given to matter, not as matter, but as enriched by a Divine power. Finally he quotes (p. 434) l66 the observa- tion of a traveller so considerable 167 and judicious as M. de la Loubere 16S that the Pagans of the east recognize the immortality of the soul without being able to com- prehend its immateriality. Regarding all this I will observe, before coming to the statement of my own view, that it is certain that matter is as little capable of producing feeling [sentiment] mechanically, as it is of producing reason169, as our author admits ; and that I most certainly recognize that it is not allowable to deny what one does not understand, but I add that we have a right to deny (at least in the order of nature) that which is absolutely neither intel- ligible nor explicable. I maintain also that substances^ (material or immaterial) cannot be conceived in their] bare essence without any activity, that activity is of the essence of substance in general ; and that the conceptions^ of created beings are not the measure of the power of lee Works, iv. 485 ; Bohn's ed., ii. 406. 167 Locke's word. 168 Simon de la Loubere, born at Toulouse in 1642, died in 1729. In 1687 Louis XIV entrusted him with a mission to Siam for the purpose of establishing diplomatic and commercial relations between that country and France. As the result of a three months' resi- dence in Siam he published two volumes DuRoyaume deSiam (1691 ; Eng. trans. 1693), in which he gives an elaborate account of the Siamese people, their history, customs, and institutions. The book still ranks as an authority on its subject. Locke's quotation is taken from vol. i. ch. 19, § 4. 169 Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. iv. ch. 3, § 6 (E. 346 b ; Q-. v. 360) : 1 The primary powers constitute the substances themselves ; and the derivative powers, or if you like, the faculties, are merely modes [faqons d'etre], which must be derived from substances, and they are not derived from matter in so far as it is merely mechanical, that is to say, in so far as by abstraction we take account only of the incomplete being of materia prima, or that which is entirely passive. And in this I think you will agree with me, sir, that it is not in the power of a mere mechanism to produce perception, sensation, reason.' Cf. Locke, Essay, bk. iv. ch. 10, § TO (Eraser, vol. ii. p. 313) ; also Monadology, § 17. 398 NEW ESSAYS God, but that their conceptivity, or ability [force] to conceive, is the measure of the power of nature : for all that is in accordance with the order of nature can be conceived or understood by some created being170. " Those who will think out my system will see that I cannot wholly agree with either of these excellent authors, whose controversy, however, is very instructive. But, to explain myself distinctly, it is before all things to be considered that the modifications which can naturally or without miracle belong171 to a subject [sujet] must arise from the limitations or variations of a real genus or an original nature which is constant and absolute172. For it is thus that among philosophers the modes of an absolute being are distinguished from the being itself: for instance, we know that size, figure and motion are manifestly limitations and variations of the bodily nature. For173 it is clear how an extension when limited gives figures, and that the change which takes place in it is nothing but motion. And whenever we find any quality in a subject [sujei], we should believe that if we under- stood the nature of the subject [sujei] and of the quality, we should understand [concevoir] how the quality can be a result of it174. Thus in the order of nature (setting 170 For Leibniz this would follow a priori from the essential unity of nature, shown in the fact that each Monad (and therefore each created being) contains within itself a representation of the whole universe. 171 E. reads ' come ' [venir] for convener. 172 Things do have an ' absolute ' original essence of s6me kind. They are not ultimate bare unities, equally capable of any kind of modification. 173 E. omits ' for.' Cf. Spinoza's Letters, 50, § 4. 174 Cf. Lettre a Amauld (1686) (G. ii. 56) : < Always in every true affirmative proposition, necessary or contingent, universal or singular, the notion of the predicate is in some way comprehended in that of the subject, praedicatum inest subjecto : otherwise I know not what truth is. ... Tfiere musi always be some foundation for the con- nexion of the terms in a proposition and this is to be found in their notions, That is my great principle, to which I think all philosophers must assent, and of which one of the corollaries is the common axiom, NEW ESSAYS 399 aside miracles), God is not arbitrarily free to give to substances one set of qualities or another indifferently ; and He will never give them any but those which are natural to them, that is to say, which can be derived from their nature, as explicable modifications of it. Thus we may hold that matter will not by nature have the attraction mentioned above, and will not of itself go in a curved line, because it is not possible to conceive how that can happen, that is to say to explain it mechanically ; while that which is according to nature [naturel] ought to be capable of becoming distinctly conceivable, if we were admitted into the secrets of things. This distinc- tion, between that which is natural and explicable and that which is inexplicable and miraculous, removes all difficulties, and to reject it would be to maintain some- thing worse than occult qualities and accordingly to renounce philosophy and reason, and to provide refuges for ignorance 175 and idleness by a confused [sourd] system which allows, not only that there are qualities we do not understand (of which there are only too many), but also that there are qualities which the greatest mind [esprit], even if God were to give it the widest possible grasp, could not comprehend, that is to say, qualities which would either be miraculous or without rhyme or reason ; and that God should usually perform miracles would certainly be without rhyme or reason. Accordingly this lazy 176 hypothesis would equally destroy our philosophy, that nothing happens without a reason, which can always be given why the thing took place so rather than otherwise.' This, of course, is radically opposed to the view of Locke. 178 Asiles de Vignorance. Cf. Spinoza, Ethics, Part i. Appendix: — Donee ad Dei voluntatem, hoc est, ignorantiae asylum confugeris (Bruder's ed., i. 220). ne rpne French isfaineante. Leibniz is probably thinking of the fallacy of dp-yds ^0705 or Ignava Ratio, to which he frequently refers in the Theodicee (cf. E. 470 b ; G. vi. 30). The fallacy is that which counsels doing nothing, because things are fated one way or another, whatever we do. Leibniz means that the hypothesis of 400 NEW ESSAYS which seeks reasons, and the Divine wisdom which furnishes them., Now as to thinking it is certain, and our author more than once allows it, that it cannot be a modification of matter that is intelligible or can be comprehended and explained by matter 177 : that is to say, a feeling or thinking being is not a mechanical thing, like a watch or a mill, so that one might conceive sizes, figures and motions, the mechanical combination of which could pro- duce something thinking and even feeling in a quantity of matter in which there was nothing of this kind — which thinking and feeling would also come to an end in the same way when the mechanism falls into disorder 178. Accordingly it is not a natural thing for matter to feel and to think, and this can take place in it only in two ways, 'one of which is, that God should unite with it a substance to which it is natural to think, and the other is, that God should miraculously impart thinking to it. In this matter, then, I am entirely of the opinion of the Cartesians, except that I extend it even to the lower animals, and hold that they have feeling [sentiment], and that their souls are immaterial (properly speaking) and no more perishable than are atoms according to Demo- critus or Gassendi 179 ; while the Cartesians, who are without reason perplexed regarding the souls of the lower animals, not knowing what to make of them if there is conservation of them (because it has not occurred to them that there is conservation of the animal itself in a minute form), have been compelled to deny even feeling [sentiment] to the lower animals, contrary to all appearance and to the judgment of mankind180. which he is speaking is a ' lazy ' one, because acceptance of it would imply that it is futile to investigate the * secrets of things.' 177 E. omits from l or can be ' to ' matter.' 178 Cf. Monadology, § 17. 179 Cf. New System, § 4. 180 See Monadology, § 14. NEW ESSAYS 401 But if some one should say that at any rate God can add the faculty of thinking to a mechanism prepared for it, I would answer that, if this took place and God added this faculty to matter, without at the same time putting into matter a substance which should be the subject in which this same faculty (as I conceive it) is inherent (that is to say, without .adding to matter an immaterial soul), matter must needs have been miraculously exalted so as to receive a power of which it is not naturally capable : as some Scholastics declare that God exalts fire so as to give it the power directly to burn spirits separated from matter181, which would be entirely miraculous182. And it is enough that we cannot maintain that matter thinks, unless there is attributed to it an imperishable soul or rather a miracle, and that thus the immortality of our souls follows from that which is natural183: since we cannot maintain that they are extinguished, unless it be by a miracle, consisting either in the exaltation of matter or in the annihilation of the soul. For we know, of course, that the power of God could make our souls mortal, although they may be quite immaterial (or im- mortal by nature), since He can annihilate them t84. 181 E. reads 'bodies.' 182 Of. Nouveaux Essais, bk. iv. ch. 3, § 6 (E. 347 a ; G. v. 360 : ' To suppose that God acts otherwise and gives to things accidents, which are not modes [fapons d'etre] or modifications derived from substances, is to have recourse to miracles and to what the Schools called obediential power, through a kind of supernatural exaltation, as when certain theologians hold that the fire of hell burns "' separated " souls. In which case it may even be doubted whether it would be the fire which would do it, and whether God would not Himself produce the effect, acting in place of the fire.' Cardinal Bellarmine (1542-1621) in his fie Purgatorio, bk. ii. chs. 10- 12, expounds a view of this kind, holding that the fire of purgatory is material fire, but nevertheless miraculously burns souls. In this opinion he openly follows Augustine (fie Civitate fiei, bk. xxi. ch. 10), and a similar view is expressed by Thomas Aquinas (Summa Theol. Suppl. P. iii. Q. 70, Art. 3, conclusion. 183 i. e. ' from their nature ' or ' from the order of nature.' 184 Cf. Monadology, § 6. Dd 402 NEW ESSAYS Now this truth of the immateriality of the soul is un- doubtedly of importance. For it is infinitely more helpful to religion and morality, especially at the present day (when many people have very little regard for revelation by itself and for miracles) 185, to show that souls are natur- ally immortal and that it would be a miracle if they were not. than to maintain that our souls would die in the course of nature, and that it is in virtue of a miraculous grace, founded on nothing but the promise of God, that they do not die. Besides it has for some time been generally known 18n that those who have tried to destroy natural religion and to reduce all to revealed religion, as if reason taught us nothing about it, have been counted suspect, and not always without reason '87. But our author is not of their number. He upholds the demon- stration of the existence of God 188, and he attributes probability in the highest degree to the immateriality of the soul 189, which may accordingly be accounted a moral certainty ; and consequently it seems to me that, having as much candour as penetration, he could quite well agree with the doctrine I have expounded, which is fundamental in every rational philosophy; for190 otherwise I do not see how we are to keep from falling back into fanatical philosophy, such as the Mosaic philosophy of Fludd m, which 185 E. omits the passage in brackets. 186 E. reads ' it has for some time been the case.' 187 In his Discours de la Conformite de la Foi avec la Raison (1710). Leibniz gives, at considerable length, an account of those who insisted on the opposition between reason and revelation, in which he traces the origin of this view to the Averroists. He approves of the condemnation of this position by the fifth Lateran Council, under Leo X, in 1512. (See E. 483 sqq. ; G. vi. 56 sqq.) Cf. Nouveaux Essais, bk. iv. ch. 17, § 23 (E. 403 a; G. v. 477); also Bayle's Dictionary, Appendix (vol. iv. p. 620, jjr"16 Eclaircissemenf). 188 See Essay, bk. iv. ch. 10, § 10 (Eraser, vol. ii. pp. 306 sqq. with notes). lf9 See Essay, bk. iv. ch. 3, § 6 (Eraser, vol. ii. p. 194). 193 E. omits < for.' 191 Robert Fludd (Eobertus de Fluctibus) was born at Milgate, Kent, in 1574 (or 1571), and died at London in 1637. After NEW ESSAYS 403 finds a ground for all phenomena by attributing them directly and miraculously to God, or into the barbarous philosophy, like that of certain philosophers and physicians of the past, who 192 still showed traces of the barbarous- ness of their time, and who nowadays are rightly con- temned, who found a ground for phenomena [apparences] by inventing for this purpose occult qualities or faculties, which were pictured as being like little sprites or elves 19 ', studying at Oxford he travelled abroad and made acquaintance with the theosophical views of Paracelsus, which he sought to make known in England through his Philosophia Mosaica (1638) and his Hisloria Macro-et-Micro-Cosmi Mefaphysica, Physica et Technica (1617). In these writings he tries to find a complete philosophy in the Old Testament and more especially in the Pentateuch. His system, if so it can be called, is a combination of Neo-Platonic doctrines with those of the Kabbala, and one of his favourite ideas is that of the analogy between the universe (macrocosm) and the human body (microcosm). Leibniz is here referring to his theory that all things flow directly from God, who continually produces the variations in phenomena by condensation and rarefaction of matter. All things are emanations from God and return into His absolute unity. Gassendi and Kepler wrote against the views of Fludd. j92 E. reads * which ' [philosophy]. 193 Leibniz is probably referring to the 'elemental spirits' of which Paracelsus (1493-1541) writes in his De Nymphis, Sylphis, Pygmaeis et Salamandris. He attributes to the ' nymphs ' the pheno- mena of water, to the i sylphs ' the phenomena of air, to the 'pygmies' the phenomena of earth, and to the 'salamanders' the phenomena of fire. Fludd also adopted this view. Possibly Leibniz may also be thinking of the elder Van Helmont (Johann Baptista Van Helmont, 1577-1644), who was a follower of Paracelsus. In the Epistola ad Thomasium (1669), § n (E. 52 b ; G. i. 23), Leibniz speaks of Van Helmont along with Paracelsus and others as representative of the stupid [stolidd] form of the reformed philosophy, absolutely rejecting Aristotle. In the same letter he refers to the ' occult philosophy of Agrippa ' (Heinrich Cornelius Agrippa von Nettesheim, 1486-1535% 'who ascribes to everything an angel to bring it to birth' [quasi obsletricatorem]. ' Thus,' adds Leibniz, * we return to as many little gods \_deunculi~\ as there are substantial forms and we approach the Gentile 7roAv0ei'cr/*os.' There may also here be a reference to the spiritus familiaris of the Italian physician, philosopher and mathe- matician, Girolamo Cardano (1501-1575). See his De Vita Propria, ch. 47, Opera (1663), vol. i. p. 44. On the whole matter, cf. Leibniz s D (! 2 404 NEW ESSAYS capable of artlessly doing what is ir4 required, as if watches were to indicate the time of day by a certain horodeictic faculty without needing wheels, or as if mills were to crush the grain by a tractive faculty without needing anything resembling millstones 195. As to the difficulty several peoples have had in conceiving an immaterial substance, it will readily pass away (at any rate in great part), if it be no longer maintained that there are sub- stances separated from matter, as in fact I do not believe that there are ever naturally 196 any such substances among created things. Antibarbarus Physicus, &c. (G. vii. 337N. See also Vaughan's Hours with the Mystics, bk. viii. chs. 4 and 5, and the Dedication of Pope's Rape of the Lock, where the * nymphs,' &c. are attributed to the Rosicrucians. Milton speaks of 'Those demons that are found In fire, air, flood or under ground.' 11 Penseroso, 1. 93. 194 E. reads 'all that is required.' 195 See Introduction, Part iv. pp. 156 sqq. 156 i. e. other than miraculously. Cf. Monadology, § 72. PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND OF GRACE, FOUNDED ON REASON. 1714. PREFATORY NOTE. THE Principles of Nature and of Grace has much in common with the Monadology ; and, indeed, it reads like a preliminary study, out of which the Monadology has been elaborated. They seeni to have been written about the same time ; and Gerhardt holds, against the view of previous editors, that the Principles of Nature and of Grace is the treatise which was written for Prince Eugene. It has been shown by Gerhardt that when Nicholas Remond wrote to Leibniz from Paris in 1714, asking for a condensed statement of his philosophy, Leibniz sent him a copy of the Principles of Nature and of Grace, with a letter in course of which he says : ' I now send you a little discourse on my philosophy, which I have written here for Prince Eugene of Savoy. I hope that this little work will help to make my ideas better understood, when taken in connexion with what I have written in the Journals of Leipzig, Paris and Holland. The Leipzig papers are on the whole in the language of the Scholastics; the others are more in the style of the Cartesians; and in this last writing I have endeavoured to express myself in a way which can be understood by those who are not yet thoroughly accustomed to either of the other styles.' (Letter of Aug. 26, 1714, quoted by Gerhardt, vi. 485 ; E. p. xxvii and p. 704 a.) Kirchmann suggests that probably Leibniz wrote the Principles of Nature and of Grace for Prince Eugene, and afterwards, thinking it insufficient, worked it up into the Monadology, which he gave to the Prince. The Principles of Nature and of Grace was first published in the French journal, L' Europe Savante, in November, 1718. There are three different MSS. of this work. The first of 406 PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE * these, which is the shortest, is divided, not into paragraphs, but into two chapters, the point of division being the end of paragraph 6, where transition is made from 'Physics' to ' Metaphysics.' In the other two MSS. the paragraph division appears, and the text from which the translation is made is that of the last and most complete manuscript. In the Principles of Nature and of Grace the arrangement of the matter is much less clear and careful than it is in the Monad- ology. But, following the lines of the division originally made by Leibniz himself, we may say that paragraphs 1-6 inclusive give an account of the created Monads in themselves and in their relations to one another, so far as these can be considered apart from God ; while the remaining paragraphs consider the nature of God as ultimate reason of the universe, and the consequences which follow from His perfection in power, wisdom and goodness. Some of the most important points in the Monadology are either passed over or very slightly treated in the Principles of Nature and of Grace. For instance, in the Principles of Nature and of Grace there is nothing to correspond to the passage in the Monadology regarding the two great principles of knowledge, and while the pre-established harmony is mentioned, it is not dwelt upon. But the connexion between the two writings, both in treatment and expression, is so close that the annotations to the Principles of Nature and of Grace may be comparatively brief. The Principles of Nature and of Grace will be found in E. 714 sqq. ; G. vi. 598 sqq. i. Substance is a being capable of action. It is simple or compound. Simple substance is that which has no parts. Compound substance 1 is the combination of simple substances or Monads. Monas is a Greek word, which means unity, or that which is one. Compounds or bodies are pluralities [multitudes] ; and simple substances, lives, souls, spirits, are unities. And everywhere there must be simple substances, for without simple substances there 1 See Monadology, note 2. Strictly speaking 'compound sub- stance,' according to Leibniz, is not ' substance ' at all. It is not substantia but substantiatum. Failure to observe this distinction was to some extent the source of Wolff's misinterpretation of Leibniz. PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE 407 8 would not be compounds ; and consequently all nature is full of life2. 2. The Monads, having no parts, can neither be made \formees] nor unmade. They can neither come into being nor come to an end by natural means, and consequently they last as long as the universe, which will be changed, but which will not be destroyed. They can have no shape [figure] ; otherwise they would have parts 3. Con- sequently any one Monad in itself and at a particular moment can be distinguished from any other only by internal qualities and activities [actions] 4, which cannot be other than apperceptions (that is to say, the represen- tations of the compound, or of that which is outside 5, in the simple) and its appetitions (that is to say, its tendencies to pass from one perception to another), which are the principles of change. For the simplicity of substance is by no means inconsistent with the multiplicity of the modifications which are to be found together in that same simple substance, and these modifications must consist in variety of relations to the things which are outside6. It is as in the case of a centre or point, in 2 To say that matter is infinitely divisible is the same as saying that there is compound substance everywhere ; for to be divisible is to be compound. But compound substances are made up of simple substances. Consequently there are simple substances or living beings everywhere. 3 If they had shape, they would be extended or spatial. But everything extended is divisible, and hence they would not be simple but compound, having parts. 4 Thus we cannot perceive Monads by means of our senses. What the senses give us is not the substance itself, but merely a phenomenon bene fundatum. l Spirits, souls, and simple substances or Monads in general cannot be known [comprehendi~] by the senses and imagination, because they have no parts/ Epistola ad Bierlingium (1711) (E. 678 a; G. vii. 501). 5 The compound, as compound, consists of partes extra partes ; but as compound, it is merely phenomenal. 6 'The simplicity of a substance is by no means inconsistent with its having within it several modes at one time. There are successive perceptions ; but there are also simultaneous perceptions. For when there is perception of a whole, there are at the same 408 PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE which, although it is perfectly simple, there is an infinite number of angles formed by the lines which meet in it. 3. All nature is a plenum. There are simple substances everywhere7, which are actually separated from one another by activities of their own 8, and which continually change their relations ; and each specially important [distmguee] !1 simple substance or Monad, which forms the centre of a compound substance (e. g. of an animal) and the principle of its oneness, is surrounded by a mass composed of an infinity of other Monads, which constitute the particular body of this central Monad, and according to the affections of its body10 the Monad represents, as in a kind of centre, the things which are outside of it. This body is organic, though it forms a kind of automaton or time perceptions of the actual parts, and even each part has more than one modification ; and there is perception at the same time not only of each modification, but also of each part. These multi- plied perceptions are different from one another, although our attention cannot always distinguish them, and thus we have confused perceptions, an infinity of which is contained in each distinct perception, because of its relation to everything which is outside. In short, that which is combination of parts in the out- side world is represented in the Monad only by combination of its modifications ; and without this simple beings could not be internally distinguished from one another, and they would have no relation whatever to external things ; and in short, as there are everywhere only simple substances, of which compounds are merely the aggregates, there would be no variation or diversity in things, if there were no internal variation or diversity in simple substances.' Lettre a Masson (1716) (G-. vL 628). Cf. Monadology, notes 12 and 20. 7 E. omits partout, ' everywhere.' 8 The idea is that each Monad is separated from every other inasmuch as it has spontaneity, i. e. an activity entirely its own ; for if it had merely an activity like motion, which passes from one thing to another indifferently, it would be united with all other Monads in a continuum and would thus cease to be a real, indepen- dent unit. 9 E. omits distinguee, reading ' each simple substance.' 10 Of course, this does not mean that the Monads constituting the body are really affected by outside things. Leibniz is here using popular language. . PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE 409 natural machine, which is a machine not only as a whole, but also in the smallest parts of it that can come into observation ". Since the world is a, plenum all things are connected together and each body acts upon every other, more or less, according to their distance, and each, through reaction, is affected by every other. Hence it follows that each Monad is a living mirror, or a mirror endowed with inner activity v~, representative of the universe, according to its point of view, and as subject to rule as is the universe itself. /And the_ perceptions in the Monad are produced one from another according to the laws of desires [appetits] or of the final causes of good and evil, which con- sist in observable perceptions, regular or irregular, as, on the other hand, the changes of bodies and external pheno- mena are produced one from another according to the laws of efficient causes, that is to say, of motions 13. Thus there is a perfect harmony between the perceptions of the Monad and the motions of bodies, a harmony pre-estab- lished from the beginning between the system of efficient causes and that of final causes. And it is in this way that soul and body are in agreement and are physically united, while it is not possible for the one to change the laws of the other u. ^4. Each Monad, with a particular body, forms a living substance. Thus not only is there everywhere life, accompanied with members or organs, but there is also 11 Cf. Monadology, § 64. 12 ' This " mirror " is a figurative expression ; but it is suitable enough and it has already been employed by theologians and philosophers, when they spoke of a mirror infinitely more perfect, namely, the mirror of the Deity, which they made the object of the beatific vision.' Lettre a Masson (1716) (G. vi. 626). 15 Ultimately, motions and desires (appetits) are different degrees of the same thing, viz. appetition, or the passage from one con- scious or unconscious perception to another. The unconscious appetition is motion or efficient cause, not setting before itself an end, while the conscious appetition or desire does set before itself an end of good or evil, i. e. a final cause. 14 Cf. Monadology, §§78 sqq. 410 PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE an infinity of degrees in the Monads, one dominating more or less over another. But when the Monad has organs so arranged that they give prominence and sharp- ness [du relief et du distingue] to the impressions they receive, and consequently to the perceptions which repre- sent these (as, for instance, when, by means of the form of the eye's humours, the rays of light are concentrated and act with more force), this may lead to feeling [senti- ment] 15, that is to say, to a perception accompanied by memory, in other words, a perception of which a certain echo long remains, so as to make itself heard l6 on occa- sion. Such a living being is called an animal, as its Monad is called a soul. And when this soul is raised to reason, it is something more sublime and is reckoned among spirits [esprits], as will presently be explained. It is true that animals are sometimes in the condition of mere [simple] living beings and their souls in the condition of mere Monads 17, namely when their perceptions are not sufficiently sharp [distingue:] to be remembered, as happens in a deep dreamless sleep or in a swoon. But perceptions which have become completely confused are sure to be developed again in animals 18, for reasons which I shall 15 The transition from the unconscious to the conscious per- ception is not by any means made clear. Leibniz is, of course, using ordinary language ; but it is difficult to see how he could translate it into the terms of his system, unless he were to content himself with saying that conscious Monads have less confused perceptions than unconscious Monads and have bodies whose organs are differently arranged. For, in Leibniz's view, the action of any one Monad upon another is purely ideal ; and there is nothing in the world but Monads. Cf. Monadology, § 25. 115 G. reads etendre, which might here be translated 'increase,' for entendre [heard], which is E.'s reading. Entendre seems more natural. 17 i. e. unconscious living beings and unconscious Monads. 18 That is, perceptions (in animals) which have passed into the complete confusion of unconsciousness are sure to pass into con- sciousness again. Confusion in perceptions is the same thing as envelopment or contraction. (Hence the petites perceptions are con- fused.) On the other hand, clearness in perceptions is the same thing as development or expansion. Cf. note 51 and New Essays, Introduction, note 74. PKINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE 4! I presently mention (§ 12). Thus it is well to make dis- tinction between perception, which is the inner state of the Monad representing outer things, and apperception, which is consciousness or the reflective knowledge of this inner state, and which is not given to all souls nor to the same soul at all times. It is for lack of this distinction that the Cartesians have made the mistake of ignoring perceptions of which we are not conscious 19, as ordinary people ignore imperceptible [insensible] bodies1'0. It is this also that has led these same Cartesians to believe that only minds [esprits] are Monads, that the lower animals have no soul, and that still less are there other principles of life 21 . And as they came into too great con- flict with the common opinion of men in denying feeling [sentiment] to the lower animals, so on the other hand they conformed too much to the prejudices of the crowd in confounding a prolonged unconsciousness, which comes from a great confusion of perceptions, with absolute death, in which all perception would cease. This has confirmed the ill-founded opinion that some souls are destroyed, and the bad ideas of some who call themselves free-thinkers [esprits forts] and who have disputed the immortality of our soul 22. 20 'As in body we hold that there is avrirvma and figure in general, although we do not know what are the figures of im- perceptible bodies ; so in the soul we hold that there is perception and appetition, although we do not distinctly know the imper- ceptible elements of the confused perceptions by which the im- perceptible parts of bodies are expressed. . . . You ask whether I believe that there are bodies which do not fall within sight. Why should I not believe it ? I think ib impossible to doubt it. Through microscopes we see animalculae otherwise imperceptible, and the nerves of these animalculae, and other animalculae, perhaps swimming in the fluid parts of these, cannot be seen. The minuteness [subtiUtas] of nature goes ad infinitum.' Epistola ad Bierlingium (1711) (E. 678 a ; G. vii. 501). 121 Leibniz probably means what elsewhere, following Scholastic usage, he calls ' forms/ Cf. Introduction, Part iv. p. 156. 22 Cf. Monadology, § 13. 412 PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE 5. There is a connexion among the perceptions of animals which has some likeness to reason ; but it is based only on the memory of facts or effects 23, and not at all on the knowledge of causes. Thus a dog avoids the stick with which it has been beaten, because memory represents to it the pain which this stick has caused it. And men, in so far as they are empirics, that is to say in three-fourths of their actions, do not act otherwise than the lower animals. For instance, we expect that there will be daylight to-morrow because our experience has always been so : it is only the astronomer who rationally foresees it, and even his prediction will ulti- mately fail when the cause of daylight, which is not eternal, ceases24. But genuine reasoning depends upon necessary or eternal truths, such as those of logic, of number, of geometry, which produce an indubitable connexion of ideas and infallible inferences. The animals in which these inferences do not appear are called the lower animals [betes] ; but those which know these neces- sary truths are properly those which are called rational animals, and their souls are called minds [esprits]. These souls have the power to perform acts of reflexion and to observe that which is called ego, substance25, soul, mind [esprit], in a word, immaterial things and truths. And this it is which makes science or demonstrative knowledge possible to us*6. 6. Modern research has taught us, and reason confirms it, that the living beings whose organs are known to us27, that is to say, plants and animals, do not come 33 G. reads ou effects ; E. omits this. 24 Cf. Munadology, §§ 26-28. 'a E. reads ' Monad ' between ' substance' and ' soul'; G. omits it. 26 Cf. Monadology, § § 29 and 30. In the Matiadology God is added as an object of the self-conscious soul. 37 All Monads have organic bodies, and the series of Monads and of organisms extends continuously from the lowest of Monads with the least perceptible of organisms up to the Monad of Monads, God. At both ends of the scale there are beings whose organs are not known to us. PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE 413 from putrefaction or chaos, as the ancients thought, but from preformed seeds, and consequently from the trans- formation of pre-existing living beings. In the seed of large animals there are animalcules which by means of conception obtain a new outward form, which they make their own and which enables them to grow and become larger so as to pass to a greater theatre and to propagate the large animal28. It is true that the souls of human spermatic animals are not rational, and that they become so only when conception gives to these animals human nature 29. And as in general animals are not entirely born in conception or generation, no more do they entirely perish in what we call death ; for it is reasonable that what does not come into being by natural means should not any more come to an end in the course of nature. Thus, throwing off their mask or their tattered covering, they merely return to a more minute theatre, where they may nevertheless be as sensitive [sensible] and as well ordered as in the larger theatre 30. And what has just been said about the large animals applies also to the generation and death31 of spermatic animals themselves, that is to say, they are growths of other 28 Cf. Monadology, §§ 74, 75. 29 Cf. Monadology, § 82. It would be inconsistent with Leibniz's general principles to suppose that a spermatic animal could have a rational soul (otherwise than in germ, as all souls may be regarded as potentially rational). For the rationality of a soul is merely a very high degree of clearness and distinctness in its perceptions, which again determines its rank as a dominant Monad. But nothing else than its rank as a dominant Monad determines the nature of the body it has. Consequently a rational soul must always have a human body or a body of some higher kind, spiritual or angelic, and the union of a spermatic animal's body with a rational soul is impossible. 30 Cf. Monadology, §§73, 76, 77. 31 E. (manifestly by mistake) omits a clause following these words. A translation of his text would be: 'The generation and death of the smaller spermatic animals in comparison with which they' [sc. the large animals] 'may be counted large,' &c. This misses the point of the sentence. 414 PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE smaller spermatic animals, in comparison with which they in turn may be counted large, for everything in nature proceeds ad infiniium72. Thus not only souls but also animals are ingenerable and imperishable : they are only developed, enveloped, clothed, unclothed 33, trans- formed. Souls never put off the whole of their body, and do not pass from one body into another body which is entirely new to them. Accordingly there is no metem- psychosis, but there is metamorphosis. Animals change, take on and put off, parts only3*. In nutrition this takes place gradually and by little imperceptible [insensible] portions, but continually ; and on the other hand, in con- ception or in death, when much ; 5 is gained or lost all at once, it takes place suddenly and in a way that can be noticed [notablement],- but rarely. 7. Thus far we have spoken merely as pure physicists™ : now we must rise to metaphysics, making use of the great principle, usually little employed, which affirms that nothing takes place urithout sufficient reason, that is to say, that nothing happens without its being possible for 3a ' So, naturalists observe, a flea Has smaller fleas that on him prey ; And these have smaller still to bite 'em, And so proceed ad infinitum.' — Swift, On Poetry. The idea of ' infinities of infinity ' is a favourite one with Leibniz, and it is closely connected with the notions underlying his diffe- rential calculus. ' For instance, we must conceive (i) the diameter of a small element in a grain of sand, (2) the diameter of the grain of sand itself, (3) that of the globe of the earth, (4) the distance of a fixed star from us, (5) the magnitude of the whole system of fixed stars, as (i) a differential of the second degree, (2) a differential of the first degree, (3) an ordinary assignable line, (4) an infinite line, (5) an infinitely infinite line.' Lettre a M. d'Angicourt (1716), Dutens, iii. 500. Cf. Monadology, §§ 65-70. 33 Cf. 2 Corinthians, v. 4. 34 Cf. Monadology, §§ 71, 72, 77. Aristotle condemns the theory of transmigration of souls in his De Anima, i. 3, 407b 13. 35 E. omits beaucoup ['much'] and reads, ' all is gained or lost at once.' 36 i. e. students of nature. PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE 415 one who should know things sufficiently, to give a reason which is sufficient to determine why things are so and I not otherwise. This principle being laid down, the first question we are entitled to put will be — Why does some- tiling exist rather than nothing ? For l nothing ' is simpler and easier37 than ' something.' Further, granting that things must exist, we must be able to give a reason why they should exist thus and not otherwise38. - 8. Now this sufficient reason of the existence of the universe cannot be found .in the sequence of contingent things, that is to say, of bodies and their representations in souls : because, matter being in itself indifferent to motion and to rest and to one or another particular motion, we cannot find in it the reason of motion and still less the reason- of one particular motion 39. And although the motion which is at present in matter comes from the pre- ceding motion, and that again from another preceding motion, we are no farther forward, however far we go ; for the same question always remains. Thus the suffi- cient reason, which has no need of any other reason, must needs be outside of this sequence of contingent things and must be in a substance which is the cause of this sequence, or which is a necessary being, bearing in itself the reason of its own existence, otherwise we should not yet have a sufficient reason with which we could stop. And this ultimate reason of things is called God 40. 37 i. e. more easily brought into existence. But if we can say even this of ' nothing/ must not ' nothing ' be ' something ' ? How can we say of that which is not at all, that it is ' simple ' and ' easy ' in comparison with other things ? :'8 Cf. Monadology, § 32. 39 Motion (which, for Leibniz, is what we should now call an abstraction) is regarded as passing from body to body and as having no definite source in the phenomenal world. The point of view is that which Descartes substituted for the Peripatetic theories, and Leibniz's point is that, while Descartes's view is good so far as it goes, it is insufficient and requires to be supplemented by a deeper explanation. 40 Cf. Monadology, §§ 36-38, and Ultimate Origination of Things, p. 338. 416 PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE 9. This primary simple substance must include emi- nently 41 the perfections contained in the derivative sub- stances which are its effects. Thus it will have power, knowledge and will in perfection, that is to say, it will have supreme [souveraine] omnipotence, omniscience and goodness. And as justice, taken very42 generally, is nothing but goodness in conformity with wisdom, there must also be in God supreme justice^3. The reason which has led to the existence of things through Him makes them also depend upon Him for their continued existence and working ; and they continually receive from Him that which makes them have any perfection ; but any imperfection that remains in them comes from the essential and original limitation of the created thing44. 41 i. e. in a higher degree. See Monadology, note 61. 42 E. omits fort [very]. *3 * There is a great difference between the way in which men are just and the way in which God is just ; but it is merely a difference in degree. For God is perfectly and entirely just, and the justice of men is mingled with injustice, faults, and sins because of the imperfection of human nature. The perfections of Gcd are infinite and ours are limited. . . . Justice is nothing but that which is in conformity with wisdom and goodness taken together ; the end of goodness is the greatest good, but in order to recognize this there is need of wisdom, which is nothing but the knowledge of the good. In the same way, goodness is nothing but the inclination to do good to all and to prevent evil, unless it be necessary in order to secure a greater good or to prevent a greater evil. Thus wisdom is in the understanding and goodness in the will. And consequently justice is in both. Power is another thing ; b\it if it comes into play, it makes the right become actual and causes what ought to be really to exist, so far as the nature of things allows. This is what God does in the world.' Meditation sur la notion commune de la justice (Mollat, pp. 60, 62 \ Cf. On the Notions of Right and Justice (1693), p. 283. ** Cf. Monadology, § 42. This is a brief statement of the main contention of the Theodicee, in so far as it endeavours to vindicate the goodness of God in face of the evil in the world. God is the source of the perfections of each Monad, because it is through His choice of the best of all possible worlds that each Monad actually exists and continues in existence. But every Monad has some PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE 417 10. It follows from the supreme perfection of God that in producing the universe He has chosen the best possible plan, in which there is the greatest variety along with the greatest order ; ground, place, time being as well arranged as possible 45 ; the greatest effect pro- duced by the simplest ways ; the most power, know- ledge, happiness and goodness in created things that the universe allowed46. For as all possible things in the understanding of God claim existence in proportion to their perfections, the result of all these claims must be the most perfect actual world that is possible. And apart from this it would not be possible to give a reason why things have gone thus rather than otherwise 4T. IT. The supreme wisdom of God led Him to choose specially the laws of motion which are most fitting and which are most in conformity with abstract or meta- physical reasons. There is conserved the same quantity of total and absolute force, or of activity [action], also the same quantity of relative force or of reaction, and finally the same quantity of force of direction48. Further, essential, inalienable imperfection ; otherwise it would be indis- tinguishable from God. And God cannot change the essence of any Monad, as it is in the 'region of ideas,' which is His under- standing. He can merely create and support, or withhold His creation and preservation. 45 Cf. Ultimate Origination of Things, pp. 340 sqq. 46 Cf. Monadology, §§ 55-58. *7 Cf. Monadology, §§53 and 54. 48 Every system or aggregate of bodies has a total absolute force, i. e. a total force belonging to the system as a completely indepen- dent system— a total force calculated on the supposition that there are no other total forces in relation to it, which might increase or diminish it. The whole matter of the universe is such a system, and consequently its total absolute force remains always the same. But total absolute force is always made up of two partial forces, i. e. forces which belong to the parts of the aggregate or system. These partial forces are (i) 'relative force* or 'force of reaction,' which is the force involved in the mutual action and reaction of the bodies constituting the system or aggregate, i. e. its internal action, and (2) ' force of direction,' which is the force involved in the external action of the system. Cf. Introduction, Part iii. pp. 89 sqq. See also Explanation of the New System, note 30. E 6 418 PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE action is always equal to reaction, and the whole effect is always equivalent to its full cause. And it is remark- able \_surprenant] that by the sole consideration of efficient causes or of matter it was impossible to explain these laws of motion which have been discovered in our time and of which a part has been discovered by myself. For I have found that we must have recourse to final causes, and that these laws are dependent not upon the principle of necessity, like the truths of logic, arithmetic, and geometry, but upon the principle of fitness [con- venance], that is to say, upon the choice of wisdom. And this is one of the most effective and remarkable proofs of the existence of God for those who can go deeply into these things 49. 12. Again, it follows from the perfection of the Su- preme Author not only that the order of the whole universe is the most perfect that can be, but also that each living mirror representing the universe according to its point of view, that is to say, each Monad, each substantial centre, must have its perceptions and its desires [appetite] as thoroughly well-ordered as is com- patible with all the rest. Whence it also follows that souls, that is to say, the most dominant Monads, or rather animals themselves50 cannot fail to awake again 49 The laws of actual 'concrete' motion cannot be deduced a priori under the law of contradiction ; but a knowledge of them involves a reference to experience. As a result of this reference to experience we are compelled to conceive body, not as mere externality of parts, indifferent to motion, but as something which always has a, force of its own. Thus bodies are ultimately or really (as distinct from phenomenally) independent forces (Monads), which differ from one another endlessly but are yet in such harmony that they form one perfectly regular system, the laws of which we can discover and state. Such a system could never have come into existence 'of itself,' by a law of blind necessity, indifferent to good and evil, like the principle of contradiction. An all-wise, all-powerful and infinitely good God must have chosen this system as the best among all possible systems. Cf. Monadology, § 51. 50 E. omits, themselves.' PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GKACE 419 from the condition of stupor into which death or some other accident may put them 51. 13. For all is regulated in things, once for all, with as much order and mutual connexion as possible, since supreme wisdom and goodness can act only with perfect harmony. The present is big with the future, the future might be read in the past, the distant is expressed in the near. We might get to know the beauty of the universe in each soul, if we could unfold all that is enfolded in it and that is perceptibly developed only through time. 51 Conscious Monads may for a time fall into unconsciousness ; but that they should remain permanently in that Condition would be against the general order of things. For the tendency of all created Monads is to advance to higher perceptions. In this advance each Monad is essentially limited to some extent ; but apart from this essential limitation, which is independent of the will of God, no other permanent limitation is imposed. Thus, if a Monad has once been conscious, it may be conscious again, for manifestly it is not essentially limited to the unconscious state. And it must some day be conscious again, for the wor]d is the best of all possible worlds, not merely on the whole but as regards each of its parts, which is equivalent to saying that the world is so con- structed that each of the Monads constituting it shall rise to the highest point of perfection (i. e. of perception and appetition) which its essential limitations allow. Leibniz elsewhere speaks of the world in terms which, with slight alteration, he would apply to the individual soul. l You are right in saying that our globe ought to have been a kind of Paradise, and I add that, if that is so, it can quite well become one yet, and it may have drawn back in order to make a better leap forward.' Lettre a Bourguet (1715) (E. 731 a ; G. iii. 578). Cf. Lettre touchant ce qui est independent des Sens et de la Matiere (1702) (G. vi. 507) : 'Always when we penetrate into the depths of any things, we find in them the most beautiful order that could be desired, even beyond what we imagined, as all those who have gone deeply into the sciences are aware ; and accordingly we may hold that the same is the case as regards all other things, and, that not only do immaterial substances always continue to exist but their lives, their progress and their changes also are regulated so as to attain a certain end, or rather to approach it more and more, as asymptotes do. And although we sometimes fall back, like lines which have bends in them, advance none the less prevails in the end and gets the victory.' Cf, New Essays, Introduction, note 74. E e 2 420 PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE But as each distinct perception of the soul includes an infinite number of confused perceptions, which involve the whole universe, the soul itself knows the things of which it has perception, only in so far as it has distinct and heightened [or unveiled] 52 perceptions of them ; and it has perfection in proportion to its distinct perceptions. Each soul knows the infinite, knows all, but confusedly ; as when I walk on the sea-shore and hear the great noise the sea makes, I hear the particular sounds which come from the particular waves and which make up the total sound, but I do not discriminate them from one another. Our confused perceptions are the result of the impressions which the whole universe makes upon us. It is the same xwith each Monad 53, God alone has a distinct knowledge of all, for He is the source of all. It has been very well said that as a centre He is everywhere, but His circum- ference is nowhere 54, for everything is immediately pre- \sent to Him without any distance from this centre. 1 4. As regards the rational soul or mind [I'esprit], there is in it something more than in the Monads or even in mere [simple] souls 5\ It is not only a mirror of the universe of created beings, but also an image of the Deity. The mind [I'esprit] has not merely a perception of the works of God, but it is even capable of producing something which resembles them, although in miniature. For, to say nothing of the wonders of dreams, in which we w E. reads relevees • G. reads revdees. Revelees (without the usual accents) looks like a slip of the pen and relevees is elsewhere used in a similar connexion. Cf. Monadology, § 25. 53 Cf. Monadology, §§ 60 and 61. 54 l The world is an infinite sphere, of which the centre is every- where, the circumference nowhere.' Pascal, Pensees, i. (Ha vet's ed., p. i). Havet traces the phrase to Rabelais (bk. iii. ch. 13^ thence to Gerson and Bonaventura, and ultimately to Vincent de Beauvais (early in the thirteenth century) who attributes it to Empedocles. It is not in any writing of Empedocles now known. See Havet's Pascal, pp. 17 sqq. 55 ' The Monads ' here means bare or unconscious Monads, while * mere souls ' means conscious souls, which are not self-conscious. PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE 421 invent without trouble (but also without willing it) 56 things which, in our waking hours, we should have to think long in order to hit upon, our soul is architectonic also in its voluntary activities and, discovering the scientific principles in accordance with which God has ordered things (pondere, mensura, numero, &c.) 57, it imitates, in its own province and in the little world in which it is allowed to act, what God does in the great world 58. 15. It is for this reason that all spirits [esprits], whether of men or of angels [genies], entering in virtue of reason and of eternal truths into a kind of fellowship with God, are members of the City of God, that is to say, of the most perfect state, formed and governed by the greatest and best of monarchs : in which there is no crime with- out punishment, no good action without a proportionate reward, and in short as much virtue and happiness as is possible ; and thisj not by any interference with the course of nature, as if what God prepares for souls were to disturb the laws of bodies, but by the very order of natural things, in virtue of the harmony pre-established from all time between the realms of nature and of grace, between God as Architect and God as Monarch, so that nature itself59 leads to grace, and grace, by the use it makes of nature, brings it to perfection 60. 1 6. Thus although reason cannot make known to us the details of the great future (which are reserved for revelation), we can be assured by this same reason that things are made in a way which exceeds our desires. 56 E. reads sans en avoir meme la volonte, 'without even willing it.' G. (from whom I translate) has mais aussi sans en avoir la volonte. 57 Sed omnia in mensura, et numero et pondere disposuistis. A quotation (frequently used in Leibniz's time) from the Vulgate, Book of Wisdom, ch. n, v. 21. * But by measure and number and weight Thou didst order all things' (R. V. ch. u, v. 20). The phrase pondere, numero, mensura occurs in the remains of Ulpian, Instit. bk. i, fragment iii. 58 Cf. Monadology, § 82. 59 E. omits * itself,' 60 Cf. Monadology, §§ 84-89. 422 PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE Further, as God is the most perfect and most happy and consequently the most lovable of substances, and as genuine pure love 61 consists in the state in which we find pleasure in the perfections and the felicity of the beloved, this love is sure to give us the greatest pleasure of which we are capable, when God is its object. 17. And it is easy to love God as we ought, if we know Him as I have just said 62. For although God cannot be perceived by our external senses, He is none the less very lovable and He gives very great pleasure. We see how much pleasure honours give to men, although they do not consist in anything that appeals to the external senses. Martyrs and fanatics (though the emotion of the latter is ill-governed) show how much influence mental pleasure \le plaisir de I' esprit] can have : and, what is more, even the pleasures of sense are really intellectual plea- sures confusedly known63. Music charms us, although its beauty consists only in the harmonies [convenances] of numbers and in the counting (of which we are unconscious but which nevertheless the soul does make) of the beats or vibrations of sounding bodies, which beats or vibrations come together at definite intervals. The pleasure which sight finds in good proportions is of the same nature ; and the pleasures caused by the other senses will be found to amount to much the same thing, although we may not be able to explain it so distinctly 64. 61 i. e. ' disinterested ' love. See Monadology, § 90, note 142. 82 ' God is love [c/wm'fos], which is known by love [amor] and is loved in being known.' Nicholas of Cusa, Excitationes ex Sermonibus, 10, 188 b. 63 For sense is confused perception. Cf. Introduction, Part iii. p. 125. 6* Leibniz does not mean, as some of his critics (e.g. Kirchmann) seem to have thought, that the pleasure we have in music or in painting is entirely a matter of the senses. What he wants to show is that even the sense-element in artistic pleasure is really of an intellectual kind, and this he does by showing that it depends upon an unrecognized perception of proportion, measure or rhythm. He elsewhere calls it * a hidden [occulte] arithmetic ' (G. iv. 551). PRINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE 423 1 8. It may even be said that from this time forth the love of God enables us to enjoy a foretaste of future felicity. And although this love is disinterested, it con- stitutes by itself our greatest good and interest, even though we may not seek these in it and though we may consider only the pleasure it gives without regard to the advantage it brings ; for it gives us perfect confidence in the goodness of our Author and Master, which produces real tranquillity of mind, not as in the case of the Stoics, who forcibly school themselves to patience, but through a present content which also assures to us a future happi- ness65. And besides the present pleasure it aifords, nothing can be of more advantage for the future than this love of God, for it fulfils our expectations also and leads us in the way of supreme happiness, because in virtue of the perfect order that is established in the universe, 65 'There is as much difference between genuine morality [morale'] and that of the Stoics and Epicureans, as there is between joy and patience ; for their tranquillity was founded only upon necessity, while ours should be founded upon the perfection and the beauty of things, upon our own felicity.' The'odicee, § 254 ; E. 580 b ; G. vi. 268. < What is called Fatum Stoicum was not so black as it is painted. It did not keep men from looking after their affairs; but it tended to give them tranquillity as regard; events, through the consideration of their necessity, which makes our anxieties and regrets useless. . . . The teachings of the Stoics (and perhaps also of some famous philosophers of our own time), being confined to this supposed necessity, can only secure a forced patience ; instead of which our Lord inspires us with more sublime thoughts and teaches us even the way to have content, when He assures us that as God is perfectly good and wise and takes all under His care, so as not even to neglect a hair of our heads our confidence in Him ought to be complete ; so that we should see, if we were able to comprehend it, that it is impossible even to desire anything better (either absolutely or for ourselves) than what He does. It is as if we were to say to men : " Do your duty and be content with what comes of it, not only because you cannot resist Divine providence or the nature of things (which would be enough to make us tranquil, but not to make us content) but also because you have to do with a good Master." And this might be called Fatum Christianum' Theodicee, Preface, E. 470 b; G. vi. 30. 424 PEINCIPLES OF NATURE AND GRACE everything is done as well as possible both for the general good and also for the greatest individual good of those who believe in it and who are satisfied with the Divine government. And this belief and satisfaction must inevitably be the characteristic of those who have learned to love the Source of all good 66. It is true that supreme felicity (by whatever beatific vision, or knowledge of God, it may be accompanied) can never be complete, because God, being infinite, cannot be entirely known ' 7. Thus our happiness will never consist (and it is right that it should not consist) in complete enjoyment, which would leave nothing more to be desired and would make our mind [esprit] stupid ; but it must consist in a per- petual progress to new pleasures and new perfections 6K. 66 ' We ought always to be content with the order of the past, because it is in conformity with the absolute will of God, which we know through what has come to pass ; but we must try to make the future, so far as it depends upon us, in conformity with the presumptive will of God or His commandments, to adorn our Sparta and to labour at doing good, yet without vexing out-selves when success does not come to us, in the firm belief that God will be able to find the most fitting season in which to make changes for the better. Those who are not content with the order of things cannot flatter themselves that they love God as they ought.' 1 Lettre a Arnauld (1690) (G. ii. 136; E. io8a). 67 According to Leibniz's system, if a Monad were to know God entirely, it would be God and would thus cease to be itself, which is impossible. Yet Leibniz regards the relation of men to God as so close that he calls them ' little gods, subject to the great God.' Lettre a Arnauld (1687) (G. ii. 125). Cf. Nicholas of Cusa, Excitationes ex Sermonibusj x. i88a: 'To be able always more and more to understand (to conform oneself to the Creator) without end, is the likeness of eternal wisdom.' 68 'Felicity is to persons what perfection is to beings.' Paper without a title (1686) (G. iv. 462). Cf. Ultimate Origination of Things, PP. 345, 348. INDEX Abstractions rightly used are not errors, 379. Achilles and the tortoise, 8 1 n. Action motrice, 92. Activity essential to substance, 90 n, 325, 397. Adamson (R.) on Fichte, i8on, Agrippa von Netteslieim, 403 n. Albertus Magnus, 260 n, 302. Algebra, its connexion with geo- metry, 76 ; relation to other sciences, 80. Alphabet of human thoughts, 85. Alsted, 376 n. Angelus Silesius (Joannes), 384 n. Animals, birth and death of, 115, 259, 413; indestructibility and immortality of, 262, 306, 374; resuscitation of, 224 n, 306 ; ac- cording to Descartes, are mere machines, 52 ; according to Leibniz, not mere machines, 300 ; animals incomparably greater than ours may exist, U4n, Ii6n; organs of animals in relation to perception, 231 ; organic body of, 253 ; souls of, 400 ; nature of animal con- sciousness, 232, 322, 364, 412. Animal spirits, 314 n. Anselm, 277. avTiTviria, 35 n, 94 sqq. Apperception, in Leibniz's sense, 34, 121 ; Locke's view, 367 sqq.; distinction between appercep- tion and perception, 126 sqq., 411. See also Perception. Appetition denned, 33, 35, 226, 407; degrees of, 51, 138; not ; a suf- necessarily conscious, 3 result of the principle o ficient reason, 71. Aquinas, 243 n ; on sensible species, 2i9n; on antecedent and consequent will of God, 270 n ; on souls of lower .animals, 302 ; on the motions of the planets, &c., 382 n; his explanation of ' eminent,' 238 n. Aristotle, 32, 155, 238 n, 255 n, 308, 358 n, 378 n ; in relation to Leibniz, 229 n ; his ethics, 293 n ; his description of place, 353 ; on the tabula rasa, 360 n ; on the motion of the skies, 382 n. Arnauld and Leibniz, 6, 298 n. Association of ideas, 232 n. Astraea, 64 n. Atomism, 23, 26, 31 ; Leibniz's relation to, 29, 30, 159; Atomism of Descartes and Locke, 124. Atoms, 223 n ; Leibniz's early liking for atoms and the void, 32; his criticism of atoms, &c., 2i8n, 310, 335, 370, 385 ; metaphysical atoms, 33 n ; atoms of substance = Monads, 33 n, 3«- Attraction (immediate) from a distance, 389. Attributes to be distinguished from modifications, 394. Augustine, 207 ; Civitas Dei, 267 n. Automata, 254, 264 n; Monads are automata, 229 ; soul a spiritual automaton, 315. 426 INDEX Averroes, 383 n. Axioms may require proof, 59. Bacon, John, 260 n, 302, 303 n. Bayle, Pierre, 226, 236 n, 375; on pre-established harmony, 249 n ; on multiplicity in the Monad, 272. Beautiful, definition of, 286 n. Becoming, principle of, 82. Bellarmine (Cardinal), 401 n. Benevolence, 285 n. Bernier, Fra^ois, 335. Birth of an organism, not absolute, 115 ; birth and death, 259, 413. Body not a substance, 98 n ; the mechanical cause of substance, 107 ; in flux like a river, 97, 114, 258, 262 n; without soul unreal, in; is soul's point of view, 112, 248 n; is momentary mind, 230 n; each body affected by all others, 113 n, 224 n, 251; infinite division of bodies, 237 ; reason for the existence of bodies, 324 n. See also Matter and Soul. Boineburg, 4. Bossuet and Leibniz, n ; and Fdnelon, 269 n. Boutroux, E., 234 n. Boyle, Kobert, 7, 370. Brahe, Tycho, 318 n. Bruno, Giordano, 34, 57 n. Buddeus, 38. Buffon, 198. Cabbalists, 155 n. Calculating machines of Leibniz and Pascal, 6. Calculation, every paralogism an error of, 85. Calculus, discovery of the differen- tial, 7 ; infinitesimal, 80 sqq. ; logical, 84 sqq. Campanella, 155. Cardano, Girolamo, 155, 403 n. Carlyle, Thomas, 388 n. Carneades, 284. Cartesians on the souls of the lower animals, &c., 411 ; imperfection of their view of perception, 224. See also Descartes. Cause, Leibniz's view of, 204 sqq. ; First Cause, 137; cause and effect an ideal relation, 106, 245 n ; effi- cient and final causes, 107, io8n, 205, 238 n, 263, 268 n, 409, 418 ; Kant on final causes, 176 ; Lotze's view, 193 ; the world a system of final causes, 107. Cavalieri, 76 n. Cell-theory of physiology, 198, 257 n. Centripetal powers, 389. Charity, 284. Choice of God among possible universes, 66, 174. Christianity in relation to natural law and the law of nations, 295. Christiern V of Denmark, 347. Churches, projects for reconcilia- tion of, 5, n, ii9n. City of God, 267, 293, 316, 421. Clarke and Leibniz on space and time, 102 n, 104 n. Cleanthes, 243 n. Clocks illustration of pre-estab- lished harmony, 45, 331 ; Foucher's use of, 320 ; Geu- lincx's use of, 43, 331 n. Codex Juris Gentium Diploma- ticus, 281. Cogito ergo sww,Leibniz's criticism of, 55- Cohesion of matter, 386. Compossibility, explanation of, 64 ; is sufficient reason, 64 ; in rela- tion to Kant's position, 1 74. See also Possible. Compounds not real substances, 96 n, 97, 109, 310, 330. Conception and perception, views of Kant and Leibniz, 171. Concours ordinaire of God, 43. Conduct, the end of, 146. Consciousness not essential to perception, 34; not dependent on organic structure, 321. Contingent truths, 57, 134, 243; demand an infinite analysis, 6 1 ; their final reason to be sought in God, 63. See also Truths. Continuity, law of, 37, 38, 83, 223n> 376; applied to motion and thought, 130; an applica- tion of sufficient reason, 71. INDEX 427 Continuous and indivisible, pro- blem of their reconciliation, 21 sqq. Contradiction, principle of, 58 sqq., 235 ; a principle of exclusion, 67 ; inadequacy of, 60 ; relation to sufficient reason, 66, 187; according to Leibniz and Kant, 172 sqq. ; according to Schopen- hauer, 184 ; according to Leib- niz and Lotze, ig6 ; its conse- quences in Leibniz's philosophy, 68. See also Sufficient reason. Con way, Countess of, 155. Copernicus, 318 n. Cordemoi, 43 n, 310 n. Created beings pregnant with their future states, 44 n, 231, 373, 419 ; imperfections of, 240, 250, 416. See Monads. Creation, emanation and figura- tion, 243 n. Cyrus, story of, 290. Death, meaning of, 115, 259, 413 ; is a sleep, 374. De Diaeta quoted, 308 n. Democritus, 155, 219 n, 306, 307 n, 352. Demonstration, 56 n. Descartes, 43 n, 155, 243 n, 352 ; Leibniz's dissatisfaction with his philosophy, 8, 9 ; Leibniz's criticisms of, 54 n ; Descartes's view of matter, 86 ; in relation to transubstantiation, 5 ; his views of matter and mind re- jected by Leibniz, 27, 128 sqq.; his proofs of the existence of God criticized by Leibniz, 275 ; his views on the immortality of the soul criticized by Leibniz, 225 n; Descartes and Leibniz on secondary qualities, &c., 375, 376 n; on the seat of the soul, 314 n ; Descartes's theory of knowledge, 122; his view of per- ception, 224 ; clear and distinct ideas, 48 ; self-consciousness, 52 ; principle of contradiction, 58 ; eternal truths, 242 n ; possible things, 64 n ; thinking and extended substance, 42 ; animals, 52 ; animal spirits, 314 n ; analytical geometry, 77 ; conservation of motion, 86 sqq., 88 n, 264 n, 327 ; nature of substance, 25 ; sensation, 52 ; soul and body, 263, 311 ; inten- tional species, 2 20 n ; on the meaning of ' eminent ' and ' formal,' 238 n ; method of doubt, 24 ; vortex hypothesis, 378 n ; Descartes's use of the idea of cause, 160 ; of the idea of God, 161 ; attitude towards earlier thought, 152, 157 ; affec- tation of ignorance, 152 n; rela- tion to Gassendi, 303 n ; Locke, I24n; Kegis,305 n; Spinoza, 24. Desire, instinctive, 138. Development and envelopment, H5, 259, 307, 374 n, 4I.4- Diderot in praise of Leibniz, 1 7. Dillmann on Leibniz, is6n; on vinculum substantiate, 119 n. Du Bois-Reyrnond, 37 n, 93 n, 199 n. Duns Scotus, 243 n, 358 n. Eckhart, Leibniz's secretary, 16, J7- Eduction of forms, 260 n. Egypt, Leibniz's project for the conquest of, 5. Empirical knowledge, 52, 233, 364, 365, 412- Enlightenment, value of, 149. Entelechies, 50, 159, 221 n, 229, 301 ; in matter, 94 n, 96 ; of compound substances, no ; dis- tinguished from souls, 230. Entia mentalia and semi-men- talia, 101. Epicurus, 264^ Equity, 287. Erdinann on Leibniz's view of space and time, 101 ; on the vinculum substantiate, 1 19 n. Ernest, Landgraf of Hesse- Rhein- fels, 298 n. Essences or possibilities, 241 n ; tend to existence, 247, 340, 342 ; essence and existence, 66 Eternal and necessary truths, 57, 120, 233, 363; conditional, 60 n, 428 INDEX 206 ; not dependent on the will of God, 57, 242 ; understanding of God is the region of, 241, 343. See also Truths. Ethics of Leibniz, 137 sqq. Eugene, Prince, 215, 405. Euler's criticism of Leibniz, 255 n. Evil, origin of, 240 n ; problem of, 346 sqq., 416 n ; leads to greater good, 349 ; evil of individuals not to be justified by good of the whole, 348. Explanation of the New System, 3J9- Extension, elements of, 329 ; not the essence of matter, 28, 94. Fact and reason, propositions of, 206. Facultas, 288. Fatum Stoicum, 423 n. Feeling an element in every per- ception, 139. Fenelon and ±Jossuet, 27on. Fernel, 260 n. Fichte, 252 n; on the spirituality of the universe, 267 n ; influence of Leibniz upon, 178 sqq. ; Fichte's Ego and Leibuiz's Monad, 180 ; Fichte and Kant, 178 sqq. Fitness or choice of the best, 243 ; degrees of perfection, 247. Fludd, Robert, 402. Fluid, perfect, does not exist, 335, 386. Fontenelte, 309 n. Force, notion of, 91, soon; conser- vation of, 90 sqq., 327, 417 ; dis- tinct from Scholastic potency, 91 n ; essential to matter, 94 ; a form of appetition, 2 26 n ; development of Leibniz's views regarding, 351 ; distinction be- tween absolute and directing force, 328n; total and partial, &c., 417. Forces proportional to squares of velocities, 92. Forms, accidental, 157 ; substan- tial, 108 n, H9n, 156 sqq.; rejected at first by Leibniz, 3 ; re-introduced by Leibniz, 159, 301 ; origin and duration of, 2 59 s<¥i' > forms in matter, 94 n ; indivisible, 302. Foucher, Simon, 319, 320 ; Leib- niz's comments on his dispute with Hartsoeker, 334 sqq. Freedom, Leibniz's view of, 141 ; degrees of, including necessity, 145 ; freedom and determina- tion, 343 ; is spontaneity and intelligence, 145 ; highest free- dom accompanied by most per- fect knowledge, 146. Fulgurations of the Divinity, 243. Galen, 314 n. Gassendi, 303^ 319, 352. Genus, distinction between phy- sical or real and logical or ideal, 394 sqq. Geometrical relations not merely quantitative, 77. Geometry, synthetic and analytic, 75 ; connexion with algebra, 76 ; analytical geometry of Descartes, 77. Geulincx, 312 n, 367 n ; use of the clocks illustration, 43, 331 n. God, idea of, in Descartes' s system, 161 ; according to Leibniz and Descartes, 57 ; inconsistency of Leibniz's account of, 175, i77> proof of His existence, 242 ; ontological proof, according to Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz, 2 74 s^.(l' > Cosmological proof, 239 n ; proof from pre-estab- lished harmony, 202, 316, 418 ; Kant on the proofs, 173; God the ultimate sufficient reason of things, 66, 238, 339, 415 ; the source both of essences and existences, 241, 343 ; the ulti- mate reality, 136; His relation to the world, 257 n, 344, 416 ;- to other Monads, &c., 243 n, 266, 304; God not the only Spirit, 385 n ; ' assistance ' of God, 43 ; love of God, 148, 286, 422, 423 ; His perfection, 240 ; His antecedent and consequent will, 270, 424 n; His justice compared with human justice, INDEX 416 n ; His understanding the region of eternal truths, 66, 24r> 343J His possibility un- limited, 240 n; His power, knowledge and will, 244 ; His choice among possible universes, 66, 1 74 ; His centre everywhere, circumference nowhere, 420 ; without body, 259 ; vision of all things in God, 53 n ; things not modes of God, I37n; ethical importance of the idea of God, 293. Good and evil, relative terms, 146. Green, T. H., on Leibniz and Kant, 168 n, 172 n. Grotius, 288, 293 n. Guhrauer, 37. Happiness, 287 n; is a perpetual progress to new perfections, 424 ; nothing more true than, 350. Hartmann, E., 199. Hartsoeker, 305 n ; Leibniz's com- ments on his dispute with Foucher, 334 sqq. Hegel, 34 ; his solution of the dualism in Leibniz, 186 sqq. ; shows that contradiction pre- supposes sufficient reason, 187 ; view of self-consciousness, 189, 190 ; his ' notion ' and Leibniz's Monad, 188. Herbart, 2 20 n ; his ' reals ' and Leibniz's Monads, 1 85 ; mathe- matical methods in psychology, 186. Herder, 198. Hermetics, 155 n. Hermolaus Barbarus, 245. Hippocrates, 251, 260 n, 373 ; on the indestructibility of animals, 308. Hobbes, 264 n ; influence upon Leibniz, 7 ; definition of space, 101. Huygens, 332 n ; intercourse with Leibniz, 6 ; pendulum experi- ment, 45 n, 332. Hypotheses, uses of, 325. Ideas, views of Descartes and Leibniz regarding clear and 429 distinct, 48 ; clearness and dis- tinctness not the sole criteria of truth, 55 sqq. ; innate ideas, 233 n> 36° sqq- ; illustrated by block of veined marble, 131, 366 ; views of Descartes, Locke and Leibniz regarding innate ideas, 125; region of ideas in understanding of God, 66, 241, 343 ; symbolizing of ideas, 85. Identity, principle of, see Contra- diction. Identity of the indi- vidual, how constituted, 133 n, 373 ; not determined by time and place, 377 n; physical and moral identity, 258 n. Ignava ratio, 399 n. Immortality of the soul, 1 16, 225 n, 259 sqq., 316, 383, 401 sqq. ; of the rational soul, 116, 307; in relation to ethics, 292, 293 n. Impenetrability, 94 sqq. Impulse in matter and bodies, 387, 388. Indeterminism, error of, 143. Indifference of equilibrium, 375. Indiscernibles, identity of, 36, 222, 369 n, 377; an application of sufficient reason, 71. Indivisible elements, how can they form a continuum, 21 sqa. Inertia of body, 95, 240. Infinite, different meanings of, 255 n. Infinitely little, 79. Infinitesimals, 81 ; a virtual re- cognition of the principle of Becoming, 82. Infinity, notion introduced into geometry, 75 ; degrees of, 414 n. Influxus physicus, 42, 46, 219 n, 333- Justice, definition of, 148, 283 ; universal, 287 sqq., 294; com- mutative, 287 sqq.; distributive, 287 sqq.; contributive, 289 n; Aristotle's sub-divisions of par- ticular justice, 287 n ; arith- metical and geometrical equality in justice, 290 n ; Divine and human justice differ only in degree, 291 n, 416 n. 430 INDEX Kant, relation to Leibniz, 168 sqq. ; his own view of his relation to Leibniz, 208 sqq. ; Kant and Leibniz on perception* and con- ception, 171 ; Kant's thing-in- itself in relation to Leibniz, 1 75 ; Kant's misunderstanding of Leibniz, 163 n ; he misunder- stands Leibniz's view of space, 221 n; his criticism of Leibniz, i6gn; Kant and Wolff, 168 ; Kant received problem of space in Wolffs form, 169 ; develop- ment of Kant's view of space, 170 ; Kant on intensive quan- tity, 22on; on the ontological proof of the existence of God, 277, 173 ; on the relation of God to the world, 177 ; on final causes, £c., 176. Kepler's introduction of the notion of infinity into geometry, 75. Ker of Kersland, 16. Kirchmann, 259 n. Knowledge, Leibniz's theory of, 121 sqq. ; how dependent on his main principles, 133 sqq. ; know- ledge at once innate and experi- ential, 126. Knutzen, 168. Language, philosophical, 85 sqq. Law, positive Divine, 296. LEIBNIZ, boyhood, i ; early studies, 1,2; university life, 2 ; gradua- tion theses, 3; connexion with Boineburg, 4 ; residence in Niirnberg, 4; secretary to a society of Rosicrucians, 4; in the service of the Archbishop of Mainz, 4 ; residence at Frank- fort, 4 ; projects of Church re-union, 5, n; residence in Paris, 5 ; visit to London, 7 ; intercourse with Huygens, 6 ; study of higher mathematics, 6 ; invented a calculating machine, 6 ; reason for writing in French, 6 ; advocated use of German for philosophical writing, 6 ; relation to Hobbes, 7 ; intercourse with Boyle, 7 ; discovery of the Dif- ferential Calculus, 7 ; study and translation of Plato, 9 ; ac- quaintance with Tschirnhausen, 9 ; Newton and the Calculus, 8 ; personal relations with Spinoza, 9, 10 ; librarian to the Duke of Brunswick, 8 ; residence in Hanover, 1 1 ; visit to Rome, 1 1 ; first publication of his philoso- phical system, 12 ; growth of his system, 12 ; writing and publication ofNouveaux Essais, T3> 3555 of TModicee, 14; his correspondence, 14 ; founding of academies, 14, 15; intercourse with Peter the Great, Charles VI, and Prince Eugene, 1 5 ; suffers from prejudices of George I, 15 ; death and funeral, 16 ; personal characteristics, 16, 17 ; principal works and editions, 18 sqq. LEIBNIZ, three chief conceptions of . his metaphysic, 47, 48 ; logical principles of his philosophy, 58 sqq. ; his view of self-conscious- ness, 53, 120, 128, 133, 234 n; his ethics, 137 sqq. ; psychology of volition, 142 n ; logic, 206 sqq. ; theory of knowledge, 121 sqq. ; his mathematics inrelation to his philosophy, 74 sqq. > anti- cipation of transformation of energy, 93 n ; optimism,66, 147 n, 248, 271, 345 sqq., 417, 424 ; on the ontological proof of the existence of God, 275 sqq. ; holds that matter cannot think, 400 ; interest in microscopy, 256 n ; eclecticism, 154, 155 ; fore- shadows the critical spirit, 154; early rejection of substantial forms, 3 ; his account of his early philosophical views, 299 sqq. ; growth of his views re- garding force and motion, 351 ; misunderstood by his disciples, 163 ; accused of borrowing clocks illustration from Geulincx, 43. — relation to Plato and Aristotle, 358 n, 229 n ; to earlier thinking, 151 sqq., 158; dissatisfaction with Descartes's philosophy, 8 ; difference from Descartes re- garding clear and distinct ideas, INDEX 43T 48 n ; Leibniz and Descartes on secondary qualities, &c., 375> 376 n ; criticism of Spinoza's Ethics, 24 n ; Leibniz and Spinoza on empirical knowledge, 70 ; relations to Newton, 8, 80 ; correspondence with Clarke, 102 n, 104 n ; discussion with Bayle on multiplicity in the Monad, 272 ; Leibniz's account of his relation to Locke, 357 sqq. ; criticisms of Locke, 13 ; criticism of the tabula rasa, 122 n, 369 ; via media between Descartes and Locke, 123; on the controversy between Locke and Stillingfleet, 398 sqq. ; re- lation to Kant, 168 sqq., 208 sqq. ; Kant's discussion of Leibniz's first principles, 208 ; relation to Fichte, 178 sqq. ; to Schopenhauer, 183 ; toHerbart, 184; to Hegel, 1 86 ; to Lotze, 190 sqq. Lemoine on the vinculum sul)- stantiale, 119 n. Lessing, 198. Leuwenhoek, 256 n, 260 n, 305 n. Liberty of indifference does not exist, 141 sqq. Life everywhere in nature, 105, 109, 112, 256,309,409. Limitation, necessity of, 340 n. Limitations of created things, 240, 250, 416, 419 n. Limits, mathematical points are, 28, 29. Locke, 36 n ; his Essay, 355 sqq. ; Leibniz's relation to and criti- cism of, 13, 123, 357 sqq.; Locke's theory of knowledge, 122 ; his view that mind may exist without thought, opposed by Leibniz, 129 ; his account of ' uneasiness,' 140 ; his account of virtue criticised, 149 n ; on the immortality of the soul, 383 n ; on the immateriality of the soul, 402 ; holds that matter may think, 392, 395 ; Locke and Descartes, I24n; Locke and Stillingfleet, 387 sqq. Logic of Leibniz, 206 sqq. ; Leibniz's early interest in logic, 2. Lotze, H4n ; relation to Leibniz, 194 sqq.; criticism of Leib- niz, 195 sqq. ; on innate ideas, 126 n; on mechanism, 192; his monadology, 194 ; teleology, 193; relation to Herbart, 191 ; on Hegel, 190, 192. Loubere, Simon de la, 397. Louis XIV, 5. Love, disinterested as distinct from selfish, 148, 269, 285 ; Divine, 286, 423. Machines of nature are machines throughout, 254, 309 ; have an infinity of organs, 309. Mainz, Archbishop of, employs Leibniz, 4. Malebranche, 305 n, 312; inter- course with Leibniz, 6 ; sense in which Leibniz agrees with him, 53 n; he might approve the pre-established harmony, 44 n. Malpighi, 39 n, 256 n, 260 n, 305 n. Materia prima, 95 ; and materia secunda, no; possessed by every created Monad, 97. Materia secunda, 96, 258 ; an aggregation, 97, 300 ; a mere phenomenon, 97 ; in flux like a river, 97, 114, 258, 262 n ; dis- tinct from substance, 96 n. Mathematics in relation to Leib- niz's philosophy, 74; Divine mathematics, 342 ; mathematical points, 311. Matter, Leibniz's theory of, 93 sqq. ; not mere extension, 28, 94 ; a mere aggregate, 300 ; in- finitely divided as well as infin- itely divisible, 39, 237, 255, 335 ; living throughout, 256; cohesion of, 386 ; primary and secondary qualities, loo ; inseparable from mind, in, 128; can matter think ? 390 sqq. ; miraculous exaltation of matter, 401 ; Des- cartes's view of matter, 86. Mechanical philosophy, 158. Mechanism, Divine and human, 432 INDEX 254, 309 ; can explain nothing but mechanism, 228n; cannot produce perception, 227, 397, 400. Melissus, 259 n, 308. Memory the sign of consciousness, 230 n; in animals, 232, 322, 364, 412. Metamorphosis in compound sub- stance, 114, 258,307, 414. Metaphysical laws in nature, 344. Metempsychosis inadmissible, 1 14, 258, 3°4, 4H- Microscopy in Leibniz's time, 256 n. Milton quoted, 404 n. Mind always thinks, 129, 369 sqq. ; likened to veined marble, 131, 366. See also Souls (rational). Miracles of reason, nature full of, 254n- Molinos, Miguel de, 384 n. Monads, history of the term, 34 ; account of, 30 sqq., 217 sqq., 406 sqq. ; the only real existences, 97 ; infinite in number, 37 ; an infinite series, 37 ; compared to ordinates of a curve, 37 n, 38 ; their production, 243 ; creation and annihilation, 219 ; ingener- able and imperishable, 36, 115, 218, 302, 407 ; qualities of, 220 ; must have both perception and appetition, 33 ; have no parts, 2 1 7 sqq., 407 ; not in space, 2 2 1 n ; not perceived by the senses, 407 n; spontaneity of, 35, 50, 274, 313 ; are incorporeal auto- mata, 229, 315, 408 ; present of each Monad big with its future, 44 n, 231, 373, 419; all its ideas innate, 125 ; its self-iden- tity not static but dynamic, 69 ; continually unfolding or enfolding itself, 113; Monads have no windows, 219 ; mutual exclusiveness, 36, 219; each as independent as if there existed only God and itself, 313 ; meta- physical atoms, atoms of sub- stance, of nature, &c., 33 n, 218 ; metaphysical points, 311 ; centres 1 or concentrations of the world, 70, 407 ; changes in Monads, 40 sqq., 222 sqq. ; correlativity of their changes, 41 ; multiplicity in the Monad, 224 n, 226, 272, 407; Monads as living mirrors of the universe, 36, 41, 253, 409 ; variously represent or implicitly contain the whole universe, 50, 248, 420 ; each represents most distinctly its own body, 253 ; elements in Monads, 245 ; each a concrete unity of soul and body, 109 ; activity and passivity of,' 105, 245, 246, 317 ; influence one another ideally, 42, 45, 105, 246 ; their mutual agreement, 313 sqq. ; their interrelation not to be realized by sense or ima- gination, 46 ; differences among Monads, 49, 55 ; degrees of per- ception, 410 ; three grades of created Monads, 50, 229 sqq., 409 sqq. ; each higher grade has characteristics of lower, 52 ; im- perfections of Monads, 240, 250, 416 ; their progress towards per- fection, 419 n ; dominant Monad, 109 sqq., 253 n, 257, 408 ; Monads in relation to Fichte s ' Ego,' 1 80 ; to Herbart's ' reals,' 185; to Hegel's < notion,' 188. See also Souls. Monadology, time and circum- stances of its composition, 215 ; relation to Principles of Nature and Grace, 215,405 ; analysis of, 216; Kant's discussion of, 209. Monas Monadum, 57, 189. Montaigne, 372 n ; on indeter- minism, 144^ More, Henry, 155. Motion, Leibniz's view of, 89 ; development of Leibniz's views, 351 ; relativity of motion and rest, 89 sqq. ; conservation of direction, 93, 264, 32 7, 41 7; Des- cartes's view of motion, 86 sqq. ; he maintains its conservation, 87, 264 n ; that it is not merely relative to rest, 88 ; and that its direction is variable, 89 ; laws of motion, according to Descartes and Leibniz, 327, 328, 353, 417; absolute and relative motion, INDEX 433 317, 318 ; absurdity of swiftest possible motion, 275. Miiller, Johannes, 192, 198. Miiller, Otto F., 163 n. Natura naturans and natura naturata, 162. Nature and grace, realms of, 268, 421. Necessary and eternal truths, 56, 120, 233, 363 ; necessary and contingent truths, 134, 340 ; their difference compared to that of commensurable and incom- mensurable numbers, 6 1 n. Necessity, different kinds of, 339 ; metaphysical and physical, 342 ; metaphysical and moral, 67, 145, 247 n, 277; necessity an infin- itely small degree of freedom, 145 ; necessity and fitness, 418. New Essays, circumstances of writing, &c., 13, 355. New System, 297. Newton on the relations between geometrical figures, 82 ; on attraction, &c., 388 ; view of space, 1 02 n ; relation to Leib- niz as regards the Infinitesimal Calculus, 8, 80. Nicholas of Cusa, 32 n, 34 n, 222 n, 248 n, 250 n, 255 n, 267 n, 424 n. Nizolius, Leibniz's essay on, 6. Nolen, L\, quoted, 65 n ; on Leib- niz and Kant, 1 78 n. Number, 329. Occasionalism, 43, 46, 333; de- scribed and criticised, 312 ; Leibniz's criticism of, 44. Occult qualities, 157, 389 n, 399, 403. Optimism of Leibniz, 66, 248, 271, 345 i=qq., 417, 424; his moral optimism, I47n. Organic and inorganic, nature of the distinction between, in ; organic beings between man and God, I2on. Organism, conception of, 31, 253 sqq. ; pervades nature, 105, 109, 112, 256, 309, 409; organisms always come from seeds, 260, 413. Ovid, 390 n. Paracelsus, 403 n. Parmenides, 155 n, 259 n, 308. Pascal, 420 n ; on mathematical infinity, 77 n. Perception, its nature according to Leibniz, 33, 135 sqq., 2 24, 370, 407 ; equivalent to multiplicity in unity, 35 ; not to be explained by mechanism, 227, 397, 400; degrees of perception, 51 n, 231, 410 ; not necessarily conscious, 34, 231, 370, 411; unconscious is symbol of corresponding con- scious perception, 47 ; confused, clear, and distinct perception, 48, 49, 105 ; never without feeling, 139 ; perceptions always leave traces, 133 n, 373; likened to projection in perspective, 136; periodicity in perceptions, 374 n ; perceptioa-and apperception, 126 sqq., 411 ; petites perceptions, 131 sqq., 230, 370 sqq. ; percep- tion and conception, views of Kant and Leibniz, 171. Perfection, meaning of, according to Leibniz, 249, 340 ; continual progress of the world in, 419 n. Peripatetic philosophy, 156 sqq. Pfleiderer, Edmund, 43. Phenomena l>ene fundata, 98 sqq., 118 ; compared to rainbow, 100 ; their reality different from that of substance, 99 n ; how distin- guished from phenomena of dreams, 99. Philosophy, fanatical or barbarous, 402, 403. Piety, 287 sqq., 291. Place, meaning of, 203 ; according to Aristotle, 353. Plant-animals, 38. Plato, 34 n, 155, 261 n; world of ideas, 241 n ; doctrine of remi- niscence, 131, 359 n; Leibniz's view of, 368. Pleasure and pain, 139 sqq.; to some extent in every soul, 140 ; pleasure instinctively sought by every soul, 141, 146, 285; un- broken pleasure begets loathing, 434 INDEX 348, 424 ; artistic pleasure is intellectual, 422. Plenum, conception of theworld as, 40, 251, 385,408. See Vacuum. Pliny, 306, 307 n. Plotinus, 155 n. Plutarch, 252 n. Pneumatics, 376. Points, metaphysical, mathema- tical and physical, 311; mathe- matical points are limits, 28, 29. Poiret, 57, 243. Pope, 198, 257 n, 349 n. Possible, definition of, 63 ; possible and compossible, 64, 340 sqq. Possible things. See Essences. Praedicatum inest subjecto, 61 n, 398 n- Pre-established harmony, 39 sqq., 246» 263, 374 sqq-» 409, 421 ; first mentioned by Leibniz, 326 ; called a hypothesis of agree- ments, 315 ; compared with Scholastic and Occasionalist theories, 42, 44, 333 ; explained by a special instance, 200 ; advantages of, 323 ; a proof of the existence of God, 202, 316, 418 ; clocks and choirs illustra- tions of, 45, 47, 331 ; might be approved by Malebranche, 44 n ; Kant's account of, 209 sqq. Preformation, 260, 412 sqq. Present big with the future and laden with the past, 44 n, 231, 373, 41?- Preservation is a continual crea- tion, 44 n, 244 n. Principles of Nature and of Grace in relation to the Monadology, 215, 405 sqq. Progression, conservation of the quantity of, 328. Propositions, categorical and hypo- thetical, 206 ; import of, 207. Pufiendorf, 293 n. Pythagoras, 34 n ; Pythagorean views, 155 n. Qualities, intrinsic and extrinsic, 222 n; occult, 157, 389^ 399, 403. See Substance. Quantity, intensive and extensive, 220n; 'negligible,' 79; Leib- niz's sharp distinction between quantity and quality, 221 n; quantitative unity, 78. See Sub- stance. Rainbow simile for phenomenon bene fundatum, 100. Reason, meaning of, 120 ; reason and imagination, 232, 365 ; reason and fact, propositions of, 206 ; ultimate reason of things, 66, 238, 337, 339, 415. See Suf- ficient Reason. Reasoning, truths of, 57, 235. Reflexion, acts of, 56, 234, 412 ; ideas of, 366. Re"gis, 305 n. Relativity, how Leibniz tries to avoid, 135 sqq. Representation the essence of the relation between whole and part, 32. See Perception. Resistance a passive force, 95. Resuscitation of animals, 224 n, 306. Rewards and punishments, 269, 304, 381, 421. Riedel, 0., on Kant, 178 n. Right, doctrine of, 282 ; precepts of, 288 ; degrees of natural Right, 287 sqq. ; voluntary Right, 295. Rorarius, 227. Rosicrucians, Leibniz's connexion with, 4. Sarmatian salt-mines, 346. Scaliger, Julius Caesar, 361. Sceptics, 155. Schelling on Leibniz, 1 79 n ; on the relation between Leibniz and Fichte, 182. Schiller, 198 n, 268 n. Scholasticism, Leibniz finds value in, 156 ; Scholastic potency distinct from force, 91 n, 123 n. Schopenhauer in relation to Leib- niz and Fichte, 183. Schwann, 198. Self -consciousness more than merely self-consistent, 59 ; im- plies consciousness of objects, INDEX 435 135 ; Leibniz's view of, 53, 120, 128, 133, 234 n ; Descartes's view of, 52 ; difference between Descartes and Leibniz, 54 ; Fichte's view, 181 ; Hegel's view, 189, 190. Self- consistency, if real, must have grounds, 59. Self-love the ground of all our actions, 148 ; disinterested in proportion as it is enlightened, 148 ; self-love and the love of God, 423. Semi-pleasures and semi-pains, 140. Sensation is confused perception, I25> 37 2 ; necessary to thought but not the essence of it, 362 n ; according to Descartes, is purely physical and mechanical, 52. Sense-experience not the source of all truth, 134, 361 sqq. ; gives only particular truths, 362 ; views of Locke and Leibniz regarding, 134. Sense-qualities are occult qualities, 362 n ; clear but not distinct, 372 n. Series, infinite, 78 sqq. Sigwart, H. C. W., 45 n. Sin and virtue, 269. Sophia Charlotte,Queen of Prussia, H, J5- Souls, class of Monads called, 51, 410 ; distinguished from ente- lechies, 230; indivisible, 302; spontaneity of, 274, 313 ; infi- nite complexity of, 252 ; each has some perception of all things, 1 1 3 n ; souls and atoms, differ- ence between the changes in, 223 n ; seat of the soul, 314, 315 n ; soul likened to an animal musician, 273 ; the final cause of substance, 107 ; souls all in- stinctively seek pleasure, 141, 146; origin and duration of, 259 sqq. ; transcreation of, 1 1 7 n ; traduction of, 260 n ; indestructi- bility and immortality of, 1 1 6, 225n, 259 sqq., 316, 383, 401 sqq. ; souls cannot remain per- manently unconscious, 230, 374, 419 ; utterly forget nothing. 252 n. See Monads. Souls, rational, or spirits, 51, 233, 265, 413 ; creation of, 117, 265 ; personal immortality of, 307 ; like small divinities, 266, 304, 424 n; are partes totales, 349; relation to God, 266, 293, 349, 420 ; to other souls and Monads, 1 16 sqq., 121, I72n, 266, 303, 410,412. Soul and body, relations between, 42, 258, 262 sqq., 31 1 sqq., 323, 331 sqq., 408 ; Descartes's com- plete separation between, 42, 263 ; mutual independence of, 334 n. ; souls never entirely sepa- rate from bodies, 105, 225, 258, 380 ; souls act as if there were no bodies, 264 ; how soul is con- scious of body, 200 ; soul not perfectly conscious of what happens in body, 1 1 2 n. Space, independent reality of, contrary to principle of suf- ficient reason, 102 sqq. ; empty space an abstraction, 102 ; for- mation of the idea of space, 202 sqq. ; Leibniz's theory of, 101 sqq. ; Kant on space, 169 sqq., 221 n ; Wolff's view, 1 68 sqq. Species, sensible, 219. Spermatozoa, 261. Spinoza, 31, 106 n, 155 n, 219 n, 230 n, 239 n, 244 n, 399 n ; view of substance, 22 ; use of the idea of cause, 162 ; on possible things, 64 n; his cona- tus, 71 n ; Leibniz's criticism, 24 n, 276; correspondence and intercourse with Leibniz, 9 ; Spinoza and Leibniz on empi- rical knowledge, 7° > relation to Descartes, 24 ; Spinoza's philosophy ruled by the prin- ciple of contradiction, 58. Spirit, universal, 239 n. Spirits. See Souls, rational. Stallo, 92 n, 93 n. Stein, Ludwig, 34 n, 43 n. Stillingfleet and Locke, 387 sqq. ; on the question whether matter f 2 436 INDEX can think, 390 ; Stillingfleet charges Locke with incon- sistency, 392. Stoics, 155 n, 243 n ; irpo\r)$is, 360 ; Stoic patience compared with Christian, 423 n. Substance, Leibniz's view of, 27; development of Leibniz's view, 1 2 ; unit of, 30 ; unity of, 98 n ; cannot be without activity, 90 n, 325, 397; analogous to the human soul, 159 ; all substances potentially self-conscious, 128; qualities of substances not arbi- trarily given by God, 399 ; spon- taneity of, 33, 200, 204, 313; intar - relation of substances, summary of Leibniz's view, io6n; mutual action of sub- stances, 317; extension not the essence of material substance, 28, 94; Leibniz on Descartes's theory' of material substance, 27 ; Descartes's account of sub- stance, 25 ; Spinoza's theory, 22. Substance, compound, 109 ; unity of, 96, 118, 310, 330; a mere aggregate, 310, 330 ; inter- relations of compound sub- stances, 251 ; classes of organic compound substances, 120; changes in, 113, 258,414; simple and compound substance, no, 217, 330, 406. Substance, simple, 27; variety in, 223. See Monads. Sufficient reason, principle of, 61 n, 62, 235, 414 sqq.j out- side the sequence of contingent things, 238, 338,415 ; synonyms for, 235 n; consequences in the philosophy of Leibniz, 69 ; rela- tion to principle of contradic- tion, 66, 164, 187 ; Descartes and Spinoza, 160, 163; Leibniz and Kant on the relation between contradiction and sufficient reason, 172 sqq.; Schopenhauer, 184; Hegel, 187; Lotze, 196. Swammerdam, 256 n, 305 n. Swift quoted, 41 4 n. Symbolizing of ideas, 85 ; of thought, 137; of whole by part, 33 ; mutual symbolizing of things, 251 n. Symbols, thinking and reasoning in, 147. Tabula rasa, 124 n, 360 sqq.; Leibniz's criticism of, 1 2 2 n, 369. Tendency or impulse, lowest de- gree of appetition, 138; tenden- cies to action, 123 n ; tendencies to motion in all things, 90. Tetens, 1 39 n. Th&odicte, 215, 216, 240 n, 337, 416 n ; writing and publication of, 14. Thomasius, Jacob, 3. Thought, self-sufficiency of, 136. Time, Leibniz's theory of, 101 ; empty time an abstraction, 102 ; its independent reality contrary to principle of sufficient reason, 103. Toland, John, 226n. Toletus, 157. Traction of matter inadmissible, 386. Traduction of souls, 260 n. Transmigration of souls. See Metempsychosis. Transubstantiation, 119; in rela- tion to Cartesian and Leibnitian views of substance, 5. Trinity, doctrine of, 244 n. Truth, two kinds of, 57, 134, 235 sqq. ; nothing more agreeable than truth, 350. Truths, analysis of, 236 sqq. ; of fact, 57 ; truths of fact require an infinite analysis, to obtain sufficient reason, 61, 237; con- tingent truths, 57, 134, 243; relation between necessary and contingent, 61 n, 134, 340 ; necessary truths not dependent on the senses, 363. Tschirnhausen's account of Leib- niz, 9. Ulpian, 288 n, 421 n. Unconsciousness, 230, 374, 411. Uneasiness, Locke and Leibniz on, 140, 142 n, 375. Unit of substance, 30; no real INDEX 437 whole without real units, 32, 217, 300 sqq., 310, 406. Unity, quantitative and geome- trical, 78 ; mechanical and organic, 321 ; dominant unity of the universe, 337. See Sub- stance. Universe, continual progress of, 350, 419 n ; contains nothing fallow, sterile or chaotic, 257 ; infinite number of possible universes, 65, u6n, 247. Unum per accidens and unum per se, 97 n, 98 n, 118. d'Urfe, Honore", 65 n. Vacuum, impossibility of, 72 n, 25711, 385, 4°8- Van Helmont, F. Mercure, 34 n, 155- Van Helmont, J. B., 403 n. Vinculum substantiate, 118. Virgil, 373 n. Virtualite in Leibniz's sense, 367 n. Virtue, definition of, 283 n. Vis viva, 92. Void. See Atoms and Vacuum. Volition not absolutely necessi- tated, 144 ; Leibniz's psycho- logy of, 142 n. Wallace, W., 18511. Weigel, Erhard, 3. Weigel, Valentine, 384 n. Weisrnann, 198 n. Whole and parts, problem of, 22 ; dynamic relation between, 31 ; relation of representation, 32 ; their relation under the principle of contradiction, 68 ; Descartes's presupposition regarding, 26 ; Atomist view, 26. Will or self-conscious desire, 138 ; frequently acts from a sufficient, not necessitating, reason, 145 ; willing to will, 142, 144 n. See Freedom. Windelband, 149. Wisdom defined, 287. Wolff, Christian, 'philosophy of, 164 sqq.; relation to Leib- niz, 165 ; misunderstanding of Leibniz, 46 n ; his point of view Cartesian, 166, 167 ; combination of Monad ology with Atomism, 166; optimism, 168; teleology, 167; view of space, 168 sqq.; relation to Kant, 168. Words like algebraic symbols. 147. World entirely in each of its parts, 50 n ; receptivity of, 341 ; its physical and moral perfection, 345 ; best of all possible worlds, 66,248,271,345,417; infinity of worlds, 65, n6n, 247 ; infinity of worlds of living beings in each particle of matter, 256. Xenophon, 290. Zeller, 43 n. °t Zopyra or semina aeternitatis, THE END OXFORD PRINTED AT THE CLARENDON PRESS BY HORACE HART, M.A. PRINTER TO THE UNIVERSITY WORKS PUBLISHED AT THE CLARENDON PRESS, OXFORD. Bacon. Novum Organum. Edited, with Introduction, Notes, &c., by T. FOWLER, D.D. Second Edition. 8vo, 15*. Berkeley. The Works of George Berkeley, D.D., formerly Bishop of Cloyne ; including many of his writings hitherto unpublished. With Prefaces, Annotations, and an Account of his Life and Philosophy, by A. CAMPBELL FRASER, Hon. D.C.L. and LL.D. 4 vols. 8vo, £2 iSs. The Life, Letters, &c., separately, i6s. Selections. With Introduction and Notes. For the use of Students in the Universities. By the same Editor. Fourth Edition. Crown 8vo, 8s. 6d. Bosanquet. Logic ; or, The Morphology of Knowledge. By B. BOSANQUET, M.A. 8vo, au. British Moralists. Selections from Writers principally of the Eighteenth Century. Edited by L. A. SELBY-BIGGE, M.A. 2 vols. Crown 8vo, i8s. Butler. The Works of Bishop Butler. Edited by the Right Hon. W. E. GLADSTONE. 2 vols. Medium 8vo, £i 85. ; or in crown 8vo, los. 6d. Fowler. The Elements of Deductive Logic, designed mainly for the use of Junior Students in the Universities. ByT. FOWLER, D.D. Tenth Edition, with a Collection of Examples. Extra fcap. 8vo, 3*. 6d. The Elements of Inductive Logic, designed mainly for the use of Students in the Universities. Sixth Edition. Extra fcap. 8vo, 6s. Logic ; Deductive and Inductive, combined in a single volume. Extra fcap. 8vo, 'js. Fowler and Wilson. The Principles of Morals. By T. FOWLER, D.D., and J. M. WILSON, B.D. 8vo, 145-. Green. Prolegomena to Ethics. By T. H. GREEN, M.A. Edited by A. C. BRADLEY, M.A. Third Edition. 8vo, us. 6d. Works Published at the Clarendon Press, Oxford. Hegel. The Logic of Hegel ; translated from the Encyclo- paedia of the Philosophical Sciences. With Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel's Logic and Philosophy. By WILLIAM WALLACE, M.A., LL.D. Second Edition, Revised and Augmented. 2 vols. Crown 8vo, i os. dd. each. Hegel's Philosophy of Mind. Translated from the Encyclo- paedia of the Philosophical Sciences. With Five Introductory Essays. By WILLIAM WALLACE, M.A., LL.D. Crown 8vo, los. 6d. Hume's Treatise of Human Nature. Reprinted from the Original Edition in Three Volumes, and edited by L. A. SELBY-BIGGE, M. A. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 8s. Enquiry concerning the Human Understanding, and an Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals. Edited by L. A. SELBY-BIGGE, M.A. Crown 8vo, 75. 6d. Locke. An Essay concerning Human Understanding. By JOHN LOCKE. Collated and Annotated with Prolegomena, Bio- graphical, Critical, and Historical, by A. CAMPBELL ERASER, Hon. D.C.L. and LL.D. 2 vols. 8vo, £i 125. Locke's Conduct of the Understanding, Edited by T. FOWLER, D.D. Third Edition. Extra fcap. 8vo, 25. 6d. Lotze's Logic, in Three Books ; of Thought, of Investigation, and of Knowledge. English Translation ; edited by B. BOSANQUET, M.A. Second Edition. 2 vols. Crown 8vo, 1 2 s. Metaphysic, in Three Books; Ontology, Cosmology, and Psychology. English Translation; edited by B. BOSANQUET, M.A. Second Edition. 2 vols. Crown 8vo, I2s. Martineau. Types of Ethical Theory. By JAMES MARTINEAU, D.D. Third Edition. 2 vols. Crown 8vo, 15*. A Study of Religion : its Sources and Contents. Second Edition. 2 vols. Crown 8vo, 1 §s. AT THE CLARENDON PRESS LONDON : HENRY FROWDE OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE, AMEN CORNER, E.G. 1/8/98 Clarenbon lF>i'ess, ©yfovb. SELECT LIST OF STANDARD WORKS DICTIONARIES page i LAW s . . . . . . -5£ . „ 2 HISTORY, BIOGRAPHY, ETC. . . . '. ,,4 PHILOSOPHY, LOGIC, ETC ,,6 PHYSICAL SCIENCE, ETC 7 1. DICTIONARIES. A NEW ENGLISH DICTIONARY ON HISTORICAL PRINCIPLES, Founded mainly on the materials collected by the Philological Society. Imperial 4to. PRESENT STATE OF THE WORK. £ g Vol. !.}£•/ Edited by Dr. MURRAY .... Half-morocco a 12 ( B ) Vol. II. C Edited by Dr. MURRAY .... Half-morocco 2 12 Vol. III. | JjJ j Edited by Dr. MURRAY and Mr. HENRY BRADLEY Half-morocco ............ 2 12 Vol. IV. Franklaw-Fyz— G-Gain-coming o 5 O 2 The remainder of the work, to the end of the alphabet, is in an advanced state of preparation. *** The Dictionary is also, as heretofore, issited in the original Parts :- >eries I. Parts I-IX. A — Distrustful each o la eries I. Part X. Distrustfully — Dziggetai 07 Series II. Parts I-III. E— Frankish. each o 12 Oxford: Clarendon Press. London: HENRY FROWDB, Amen Corner, B.C. ENGLISH AND ROMAN LA W. A Hebrew and English Lexicon of the Old Testament, with an Appendix containing the Biblical Aramaic, based on the Thesaurus and Lexicon of Gesenius, by Francis Brown, D.D., S. K. Driver, D.D., and C. A. Briggs, D.D. Parts I-VI. Small 4to, 2s. 6d. each. Thesaurus Syriacus : collegerunt Quatremere, Bernstein, Lorsbacli, Arnoldi, Agrell, Field, Roediger: edidit R. Payne Smith, S.T.P. Vol. I, containing Fasciculi I-V, sm. fol., 5?. 55. *„* The First Five Fasciculi may also be had separately. Fasc. VI. iZ. is. ; VII. iZ. us. 6d.; VIII. iZ. i6s. ; IX. iZ.ss.; X. Pars. 1. 1?. 16?. A Compendious Syriac Dictionary, founded upon the above. Edited by Mrs. Margoliouth. Part I. Small 4to, 8s. 6d. net. Part II. Immediately. A Sanskrit-English Dictionary. Etymologically and Philologi- cally arranged. By Sir M. Monier- Williams, D.C.L. 4to. il. 2s. A Greek-English Lexicon. By H. G. Liddell, D.D., and Robert Scott, D.D. Eighth Edition, Revised. 4to. iZ. i6s. An Etymological Dictionary of the English Language, arranged on an Historical Basis. By W. W. Skeat, Litt.D. Third Edition. 4^0. 2l. 45. A Middle-English Dictionary. By F. H. Stratmann. A new edition, by H. Bradley, M.A. 4to, half-morocco, iZ. us. 6d. The Student's Dictionary of Anglo-Saxon. By H. Sweet, M.A., Ph.D., LL.D. Small 4to, 8s. 6d. net. An Anglo-Saxon Dictionary, based on the MS. collections of the late Joseph Bosworth, D.D. Edited and enlarged by Prof. T. N. Toller, M.A. Parts I-III. A-SAR. 4to, stiff covers, 155. each. Part IV, § ij SAR-SWIDRIAN. Stiff covers, 8s. 6d. Part IV, § 2, SWff>-SNEL- tTMEST, 1 8s. 6d. *£* A Supplement, which will complete the Work, is in active preparation. An Icelandic-English Dictionary, based on the MS. collections of the late Richard Cleasby. Enlarged and completed by G. Vigfusson, M.A. 4to. 3*. 7s. 2. LAW. Anson. Principles of the English Law of Contract, and of Agency in its Relation to Contract. By Sir W. R. Anson, D.C.L. Eighth Edition. With Appendix of American Cases. 8vo. i os. 6d. Law and Custom of the Constitution. 2 vols. 8vo. Part I. Parliament. Third Edition. I2s. 6d. Part II. The Crown. Second Edition. 145. Baden-Powell. Land-Systems of British India ; being a Manual of the Land-Tenures, and of the Sys- tems of Land-Revenue Adminis- tration prevalent in the several Provinces. By B. H. Baden-Powellj C.I.E. 3 vols. 8vo. $1. 35. Digby. An Introduction to the History of the Law of Real Property. By Kenelm E. Digby, M.A. Fifth Edition. 8vo. 125. 6d. Oxford: Clarendon Press. LAW. Grueber. Lex Aquilia. By Erwin Grueber, Dr. Jur., M.A. 8vo. i os. 6d. Eall. International Law. ByW.E. Hall, M.A. Fourth Edition. 8vo. 22s. 6d. A Treatise onthe Foreign Powers and Jurisdiction of the British Crown. ByW.E. Hall, M.A. 8vo. los. 6d. Eolland. Elements of Juris- prudence. By T. E. Holland, D.C.L. Eighth Edition. 8vo. los. 6d. The European Concert in the Eastern Question; a Collection of Treaties and other Public Acts. Edited, with Introductions and Notes, by T. E. Holland, D.C.L. 8vo. I2s. 6d. - — Gentilis, Alberici, De lure Belli Libri Tres. Edidit T. E. Holland, I.C.D. Small 4to, half- morocco, 2 IS. The Institutes of Jus- tinian, edited as a recension of the Institutes of Gaius, by T. E. Holland, D.C.L. Second Edition. Extra fcap. 8vo. 55. Holland and Shadwell. Select Titles from the Digest of Justinian. By T. E. Holland, D.C.L., and C. L. Shadwell, D.C.L. 8vo. 143. Also sold in Parts, in paper covers — Part I. Introductory Titles. 2s. 6d. Part II. Family Law. is. Part III. Property Law. 2s. 6d. Part IV. Law of Obligations (No. i ), 3s. 6d. (No. 2), 4s. 6d. Ilbert. The Government of India. Being a Digest of the Statute Law relating thereto. With Historical Introduction and Illustrative Documents. By Sir Courtenay Ilbert, K.C.S.I. 8vo, half-roan. 21 s. Markby. Elements of Law considered with reference to Principles of GeneralJurisprudence. By SirWilliam Markby, D.C.L. Fifth Edition. 8vo. I2s. 6d. Moyle. Imperatoris lus- tiniani Institutionum Libri Quattuor; with Introductions, Commentary, Excursus and Translation. ByJ. B. Moyle, D.C.L. Third Edition. 2vols. 8vo. Vol. I. 1 6s. Vol. II. 6s. Contract of Sale in the Civil Law. By J. B. Moyle, D.C.L. 8vo. IDS. 6d. Pollock and Wright. An Essay on Possession in the Common Law. By Sir F. Pollock, Bart., M.A., and Sir K.S. Wright, B.C.L. 8vo. Ss.6d. Poste. Gaii Institutionum Juris Civilis Commentarii Quattuor ; or, Elements of Roman Law by Gaius. With a Translation and Commen- tary by Edward Poste, M.A. Third Edition. 8vo. i8s. Raleigh. An Outline of the Law of Property. By Thos. Raleigh, M.A. 8vo. 75. 6d. Sohm. Institutes of Roman Law. By Rudolph Sohm. Trans- lated by J. C. Ledlie, B.C.L. With an Introductory Essay by Erwin Grueber, Dr. Jur., M.A. 8vo. i8s. Stokes. The Anglo-Indian Codes. By Whitley Stokes, LL.D. Vol. I. Substantive Law. 8vo. 303. Vol. II. Adjective Law. 8vo. 355 First and Second Supplements to the above, 1887-1891. 8vo. 6s. 6d. Separately, No. i, 2s.6d.; No. 2,45.6^. London : HENRY FKOWDE, Amen Corner, E.G. HISTORY, BIOGRAPHY, ETC. 3. HISTORY, BIOGRAPHY, ETC. Adamnani Vita 8. Columbae. Ed. J. T. Fowler, D.C.L. Crown 8vo, half-bound, 8s. 6d. net (with translation, gs. 6d. net}. Aubrey. ' Brief Lives ',' chiefly of Contemporaries, set down by John Aubrey, between the Tears 1669 and 1696. Edited from the Author's MSS., by ANDREW CLARK, M.A., LL.D. With Facsimiles. 2 vols. 8vo. 255. BsLQd&QHistoria Ecclesiastica, etc. Edited by C. Plummer, M.A. 2 vols. Crown 8vo, 2 is. net. Bedford (W.K.B,.). The Blazon of Episcopacy. Being the Arms borne by, or attributed to, the Arch- bishops and Bishops of England and Wales. With an Ordinary of the Coats described and of other Episcopal Arms. Second Edition, Revised and Enlarged. With One Thousand Illustrations. Sm. 4to, buckram, 315. 6d. net. BoswelPs Life of Samuel Johnson, LL.D. Edited by G. Birk- beck Hill, D.C.L. In six volumes, medium 8vo. With Portraits and Facsimiles. Half-bound, 3*. ss. Bright. Chapters of Early English Church History. By W. Bright, D.D. Third Edition. He- vised and Enlarged. With a Map. 8VO. 12S. Casaubon (Isaac). 1559-1614. By Mark Pattison. 8vo. i6s. Clarendon's History of the Rebellion and Civil Wars in England. Re-edited from a fresh collation of the original MS. in the Bodleian Library, with marginal dates and occasional notes, by W. Dunn Macray, M.A., F.S.A. 6 vols. Crown 8vo. 2l. 55. Dubois and Beauchamp. Hindu Manners, Customs, and Cere- monies. By the ABBE J. A. DUBOIS. Translated from the Author's later French MS. and Edited by HENRY K. BEAUCHAMP. With Prefatory Note by the Paght Hon. F. MAX MULLER, and Portrait. 8vo, 155. net. Earle. Handbook to the Land- Charters, and other Saxonic Documents. By John Earle, M. A. Crown 8 vo. 1 6s. Freeman. The History of Sicily from the Earliest Times. Vols. I. and II. 8vo, cloth, 2l. 2s. Vol. III. The Athenian and Carthaginian Invasions. 245. Vol. IV. From the Tyranny of Dionysios to the Death of Agathokles. Edited by Arthur J. Evans, M.A. 21*. Freeman. The Reign of William Eufus and the Accession of Henry the First. By E. A. Freeman, D.C.L. 2 vols. 8vo. il. i6s. Gardiner. The Constitutional Documents of the Puritan Revolution, 1628-1660. Selected and Edited by Samuel Rawson Gardiner, M.A. Crown 8vo. 95* Gross. The Gild Merchant; a Contribution to British Municipal History. By Charles Gross, Ph.D. 2 vols. Svo. 245. Hastings. Hastings and the RohiUa War. By Sir John Strachey, G. C.S.I. Svo, cloth, i os. 6d. Hill. Sources for Greek History between the Persian and Pelopon- nesian Wars. Collected and arranged by G. F. Hill, M.A. Svo. IDS. 6d. Hodgkin. Italy and her In- vaders. With Plates and Maps. By T. Hodgkin, D.C.L. Vols. I-II. Second Edition. 2l. 2s. Vols. III-IV. Second Edition. il. 1 6s. Vols. V-VI. il. i6s. Oxford : Clarendon Press. HISTORY, BIOGRAPHY, ETC. Jackson. The Church of St. Mary the Virgin, Oxford. By T. G. Jackson, M.A., R.A. With Twenty- four full-page Illustrations, and numerous Cuts in the Text. Demy 4to, half-bound, $6s. net; or in vellum, gilt top and morocco labels, &c., 42S. net. Fohnson. Letters of Samuel Johnson,LL.D. Collected and Edited by G. Birkbeck Hill, D.C.L. 2 vols. half-roan, 28s. — Johnsonian Miscellanies. By the same Editor. 2 vols. Medium 8vo, half-roan, 28s. Kitchin. A History of France. With Numerous Maps, Plans, and Tables. By G. W. Kitchin, D.D. In three Volumes. Third Edition. Crown 8vo, each los. 6d. Vol. I. to 1453. Vol. II. 1453- 1624. Vol. III. 1624-1793. Lewis (Sir G. Cornewall). An Essay on the Government of De- pendencies. Edited by C. P. Lucas, B.A. 8vo^ half- roan. 145. Lucas. Introduction to a Historical Geography of the British Colonies. By C. P. Lucas, B.A. With Eight Maps. Crown 8vo. 4s. 6d. Historical Geography of the British Colonies: Vol. I. The Mediterranean and Eastern Colonies (exclusive of India). With Eleven Maps. Crown 8vo. 5s. Vol. II. The West Indian Colo- nies. With Twelve Maps. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. Vol. III. West Africa. With Five Maps. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. Vol. IV. South and East Africa. Historical and Geographical. With Ten Maps. Crown 8vo. 95. 6d. Also Vol. IV in two Parts — Part I. Historical, 6s. 6d. Part II. Geographical, 35. 6d. Ludlow. The Memoirs of Edmund Ludlow, Lieutenant- General of the Horse in the Army of the Common- wealth of England, 1625-1672. Edited by C. H. Firth, M.A. 2 vols. 8vo. iZ. 1 6s. Machiavelli. II Principe. Edited by L. Arthur Burd, M.A. With an Introduction by Lord Acton. 8vo. i4s. Prothero. Select Statutes and other Constitutional Documents, illustra- tive of the Beigns of Elizabeth and James L Edited by G. W. Prothero, M.A. Crown 8vo. los. 6d. Select Statutes and other Documents bearing on the Constitutional History of England, from A.D. 1307 to 1558. By the same Editor. [In Preparation.'} Ramsay (Sir J. H.). Lancaster and York. A Century of English History (A.D. 1399-1485). 2 vols. 8vo. With Index, 37s. 6d. Ramsay (W. M.). The Cities and Bishoprics ofPhrygia. By W. M. Ramsay, D.C.L., LL.D. Vol.1. Parti. The Lycos Valley and South-Western Phrygia. Royal 8vo. 1 8s. net. Vol. I. Part II. West and West- Central Phrygia. 2 is. net. Ranke. A History of Eng- land, principally in the Seventeenth Century. By L. von Ranke. Trans- lated under the superintendence of G. W. Kitchin, D.D., and C. W. Boase, M.A. 6 vols. 8vo. 635. Revised Index, separately, is. Rashdall. The Universities of Europe in the Middle Ages. By Hast- ings Rashdall, M.A. 2 vols. (in 3 Parts) 8vo. With Maps. 2l. 55., net. London : HENRY FKOWDE, Amen Corner, B.C. PHILOSOPHY, LOGIC, ETC. Smith's Lectures on Justice, Police, Revenue and Arms. Edited, with Introduction and Notes, by Edwin Cannan. 8vo. los. 6d. net. Wealth of Nations. With Notes, by J. E. Thorold Rogers, M.A. 2 vols. 8vo. 2 is. Stephens. The Principal Speeches of the Statesmen and Orators of the French Revolution, 1789-1795. By H. Morse Stephens. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 2 is. Stubbs. Select Charters and other Illustrations of English Constitu- tional History, from the Earliest Times to the Reign of Edward I. Arranged and edited by W. Stubbs, D.D., Lord Bishop of Oxford. Eighth Edition. Crown 8vo. 8s. 6d. The Constitutional His- tory of England, in its Origin and Development. Library Edition. 3 vols. Demy 8vo. 2l. 8s. Also in 3 vols. crown 8vo, price i2s. each. Stubbs. Seventeen Lectures on the Study of Mediaeval and Modern History. Crown 8vo. 8s. 6d. Registrum Sacrum Anglicanum. An attempt to exhibi the course of Episcopal Successk in England. By W. Stubbs, D.] Small 4to. Second Edition. IDS. Swift (P. D.). The Life a-3 Times of James the First of At By F. D. Swift, B.A. 8vo. I2S. Vinogradoff*. Villainage England. Essays in English M( aeval History. By Paul Vinogradoff, Professor in the University of Moscow. 8vo, half-bound. i6s. Woodhouse. Aetolia; its Geography, Topography, and Antiqui- ties. By WILLIAM J. WOODHOUSE, M.A., F.R.G.S. With Maps and Illustrations. Royal 8vo. price 2 is. net. 4. PHILOSOPHY, LOGIC, ETC. Bacon. The Essays. With In- troduction and Illustrative Notes. By S. H. Reynolds, M.A. 8vo, half- bound. I2s. 6d. Novum Organum. Edited, with Introduction, Notes, &c., by T. Fowler, D.D. Second Edition. 8vo. 155. Berkeley. The Works of George Berkeley, D.D., formerly Bishop of Cloyne ; including many of his urrit- ings hitherto unpublished. With Pre- faces, Annotations, and an Account of his Life and Philosophy. By A., Campbell Fraser, Hon. D.C.L., LL.JX 4 vols. Svo. 2l. 1 8s. The Life, Letters, &c., separately, i6s. Bosanquet. Logic; or, the Morphology of Knowledge. By B. Bosanquet, M.A. Svo. 2 is. Butler. The Works of Joseph Butler, D.C.L. ; sometime LordBish op of Durham. Divided into sections, with sectional headings, an index to each volume, and some occasional notes; also prefatory matter. Edited by the Right Hon. W. E. Gladstone. 2 vols. Medium Svo. 285. Fowler. The Elements of De- ductive Logic, designed mainly for the use of Junior Students in the Universities. By T. Fowler, D.D. Tenth Edition. with a Collection of Examples. Extra fcap. Svo. 35. 6d. The Elements of Induc- tive Logic, designed mainly for the use of Students in the Universities. By the same Author. Sixth Edition. Extra fcap. Svo. 6s. Oxford : Clarendon Press. PHYSICAL SCIENCE, ETC. Fowler. Logic ; Deductive and Inductive, combined in a single volume. Extra fcap. 8vo. ys. 6d. Fowler and Wilson. The Principles of Morals. By T. Fowler, D.D., and J. M. Wilson, B.D. 8vo, cloth, 145. Green. Prolegomena to Ethics. By T. H. Green, M.A. Edited by A. C. Bradley, M.A. 8vo. 125. 6d. Hegel. The Logic of Hegel. Translated from the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences. With Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel's Logic and Philosophy. By W. Wal- lace, M.A. Second Edition, Revised and Augmented. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. i os. 6d. each. Hegel's Philosophy of Mind. Translated from the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences. With Five Introductory Essays. By Wil- liam Wallace, M.A., LL.D. Crown 8vo. io«. 6d. Hume's Treatise of Human Nature. Edited, with Analytical Index, by L. A. Selby-Bigge, M.A. Second Edition. Crown 8vo. 8s. — Enquiry concerning the Human Understanding, and an Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals. Edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge, M.A. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. Locke. An Essay Concern- ing Human Understanding. By John Locke. Collated and Annotated, with Prolegomena, Biographical, Critical, and Historic, by A. Camp- bell Fraser, Hon. D.C.L., LL.D. 2 VOls. 8VO. ll. I2S. Lotze's Logic, in Three Books ; of Thought, of Investigation, and of Knowledge. English Translation ; edited by B. Bosanquet, M.A. Second Edition. 2 vols. Cr. 8vo. I2s. Metaphysic, in Three Books ; Ontology, Cosmology, and Psychology. English Translation ; edited by B. Bosanquet, M.A. Second Edition. 2 vols. Cr. 8vo. 1 2s. Martineau. Types of Ethical Theory. By James Martineau, D.D. Third Edition. 2 vols. Cr. 8vo. 155. A Study of Religion : its Sources and Contents. Second Edition. 2 vols. Cr. 8vo. i5s. Selby-Bigge. British Moral- ists. Selections from Writers prin- cipally of the Eighteenth Century. Edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge, M.A. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. i8s. 5. PHYSICAL SCIENCE, ETC. De Bary. Comparative Ana* tomy of the Vegetative Organs of the Phanerogams and Ferns. By Dr. A. de Bary. Translated by F. O. Bower, M.A., and D. H. Scott, M.A. Royal 8vo. il. 2s. 6d. De Bary. Comparative Mor- phology and Biology of Fungi, Mycetosoa Chambers. A Handbook of Descriptive and Practical Astronomy. By G. F. Chambers, F.R.A.S. Fourth Edition, in 3 vols. Demy 8vo. Vol. I. The Sun, Planets, and Comets. 2 is. Vol. II. Instruments and Prac- tical Astronomy. 2 is. Vol. III. The Starry Heavens. 145. London : HENRY FBOWPB, Amen Corner, B.C. PHYSICAL SCIENCE, ETC. and Bacteria. By Dr. A. de Bary. Translated by H. E. F. Garnsey, M.A. Revised by Isaac Bayley Balfour, M. A., M.D. , F.E.S. Royal Svo, half-morocco, iZ. 2s. 6d. DeBary. Lectures on Bacteria. By Dr. A. de Bary. Second Im- proved Edition. Translated by H. E. F. Garnsey, M.A. Revised by Isaac Bayley Balfour, M.A., M.D., F.R.S. Crown Svo. 6s. Druce. The Flora of Berk- shire. Being a Topographical and Historical Account of the Flowering Plants and Ferns found in the County, with short Biographical Notices. By G. C. Druce, Hon. M.A. Oxon. Crown Svo, i6s. net. Goebel. Outlines of Classifi- cation and Special Morphology of Plants. By Dr. K. Goebel. Translated by H. E. F. Garnsey, M.A. Revised by Isaac Bayley Balfour, M.A., M.D., F.R.S. Royal Svo, half-morocco, Sachs. A History of Botany. Translated by H. E. F. Garnsey, M.A. Revised by I. Bayley Balfour, M.A.,M.D.,F.R.S. Crown Svo. los. Fossil Botany. Being an In- troduction to Palaeophytology from the Standpoint of the Botanist. By H. Graf zu Solms-Laubach. Translated by H. E. F. Garnsey, M.A. Revised by I. Bayley Balfour, M.A., M.D., F.R.S. Royal Svo, half-morocco, iSs. Biological Series. I. The Physiology of Nerve, of Muscle, and of the Electrical Organ. Edited by J. Burdon Sanderson, M.D., F.R.SS. L.&E. Medium Svo. iZ. is. II. The Anatomy of the Frog. By Dr. Alexander Ecker, Professor in the University of Freiburg. Translated, with numerous Annotations and Additions, by G. Haslam, M.D. Med. Svo. 2 is. IV. Essays upon Heredity and Kindred Biological Problems. By Dr. A. Weismann. Authorized Translation. Crown Svo. Vol. I. Edited by E. B. Poulton, S. Schonland,and A. E. Shipley. Second Edition. 75. 6d. Vol. II. Edited by E. B. Poulton, and A. E. Shipley. 55. Elliott. An Introduction to the Algebra of Quantics. By E. B. Elliott, M.A. Svo. 155. Johnston. An Elementary Treatise on Analytical Geometry, with Numerous Examples. By W. J. Johnston, M.A. (R.U.I.) Crown 8vo. Price reduced to 6s. Prestwich. Geology, Chemi- cal, Physical, and Stratigraphical. By Sir Joseph Prestwich, M.A., F.R.S. In two Volumes. 3?. is. Price. A Treatise on the Measurement of Electrical Resistance. By W. A. Price, M.A., A.M.I.C.F Svo. 145. Ojfovfc AT THE CLARENDON PKESS JSonfcon, £fcm6ur£$, *n& (Uciv HENRY FROWDE 14 DAY USE RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED LOAN DEPT. This book is due on the last date stamped below, or on the date to which renewed. Renewed books are subject to immediate recall. NO!/ S'63-9AM LD S '64 -3 p| JAillJ LD 21A-40wj-4,'63 (D6471slO)476B General Library University of California Berkeley 23247