n ctipp ^ A SYSTEM OF LOGIC EATIOCINATIVE AND INDUCTIVE BEING A CONNECTED VIEW OF THE PRINCIPLES OF EVIDENCE AND THE METHODS OF SCIENTIFIC INVESTIGATION BY JOHN STUART MILL NEW IMPEESSION LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. 39 PATEKNOSTER ROW, LONDON FOURTH AVENUE & 30th STREET, NEW YORK BOMBAY, CALCUTTA, AND MADRAS 1919 All rights reserved Aq\S Cop- 1006443 > PEEFACE TO THE FIEST EDITION. This book makes no pretence of giving to the Avorld a new theory of the intellectual operations. Its claim to attention, if it possess any, is grounded on the fact that it is an attempt not to supersede, but to embody and systematise, the best ideas which have been either promulgated on its subject by speculative writers, or con- formed to by accurate thinkers in their scientific inquiries. To cement together the detached fragmeuts of a subject never yet treated as a whole ; to harmonise the true portions of discordant theories, by supplying the links of thought necessary to connect them, and by disentangling them from the errors with which they are always more or less interwoven ; must necessarily require a con- siderable amount of original specnlation. To other originality than this, the present work lays no claim. In the existing state of the cultivation of the sciences, there would be a very strong presumption against any one who should imagine that he had eftected a revolution in the theory of the investigation of truth, or added any funda- mentally new process to the practice of it. The improvement which remains to be etiected in the metliotls of philosophising (and tliQ author believes that they have much need of improvement) can only consist in performing more systematically and accurately operations; with which, at least in their elementary form, the human intellect in some one or other of its employments is already familiar. In the portion of the work which treats of Ratiocination, the author has not deemed it necessary to enter into technical details which may be obtained in so perfect a shape from the existing treatises on what is termed the Logic of the Schools. In the con- tempt entertained by many modern philosophers for the syllogistic art, it will be seen that he by no means participates ; though the scientific theory on Avhich its defence is usually rested appears to him erroneous : and the view which he has suggested of the nature and functions of the Syllogism may, perhaps, afford the means of con- iv PREFACE. cUiating the principles of the art with as much as is well grounded in the doctrines and objections of its assailants. The same abstinence from details could not be observed in the First Book, on Names and Propositions, because many useful prin- ciples and distinctions which were contained in the old Logic have been gradually omitted from the writings of its later teachers ; and it appeared desirable both to revive these, and to reform and rationa lise the philosophical foundation on which they stood. The earlier chapters of this preliminary Book will consequently appear, to some readers, needlessly elementary and scholastic. But those who knoAV in what darkness the nature of our knowledge, and of the processes by which it is obtained, is often involved by a confused apprehen- sion of the import of the different classes of Words and Assertions, will not regard these discussions as either frivolous or irrelevant to the topics considered in the latter Books. On the subject of Induction, the task to be performed was that of generalising the modes of investigating truth and estimating evidence, by which so many important and recondite laws of nature have, in the various sciences, been aggregated to the stock of human knowledge. That this is not a task free from difficulty may be presumed from the fact, that even at a very recent period, eminent writers (among whom it is sufficient to name Archbisliop Wluitely, and the author of a celebrated article on Bacon in the Edinhiirgh Review) have not scrupled to pronounce it impossible.* The author has endeavoured to combat their theory in the manner in Avliich Diogenes confuted the sceptical reasonings against the possibility of motion ; remembering that Diogenes' argument would have been equally conclusive, thongh his individual perambulations might not have extended beyond the circuit of his own tub. Whatever may be the value of what tlie author has succeeded in effecting on this branch of his subject, it is a duty to acknowledge that for much of it he has been indebted to several important treatises, partly historical and partly philosophical, on the generalities and pro- cesses of physical science, which have been published within the last few years. To these treatises, and to their authors, he has endeavoured to do justice in the body of the work. But as with one of these * In the later editions of Archbishop Whately's Logic, he states his meaning' to be, not that "rules" for the ascertainment of truths by inductive investigation cannot be laid dow^n, or that tbey may not be " of eminent service," but that they "must always be comparatively vague and general, and incapable of being built up into a regular demonstrative theory like that of the Syllogism." (Book iv. ch. iv. § 3.) And he observes, that to devise a system for this purpose, capable of being "brought into a scientific form," would be an achievement which "he must be more sanguine than scientific who expects." (Book iv. ch. ii. § 4.) To effect this, liowever, being the express object of the portion of the present work which treats of Induction, the words in the text are no overstatement of the difference of opinion between Arch- bishop Whately and me on the subject. t^REFACEJ. V writers, Dr. Wliewell, he lias occasion frequently to express ditferences of opinion, it is more particularly incumbent on him in this place to declare, that without the aid derived from the facts and ideas contained in that gentleman's History of the Inductive Sciences, the corresponding portion of this work would probably not have been written. The concluding Book is an attempt to contribute towards the solu- tion of a question, which the decay of old opinions, and the agitation that disturbs Euiopean society to its inmost depths, render as impor- tant in the present day to the practical interest of human life, as it must at all times be to the completeness of our speculative know- ledge : viz. Whether moral and social phenomena are really exceptions to the general certainty and uniformity of the course of nature ; and how far the methods, by which so many of the laws of the physical world have been numbered among truths irrevocably acquired and universally assented to, can be made instrumental to the formation of a similar body of received doctrine in moral and political science. PREFACE TO THE THIRD AND FOURTH EDITIONS. Several criticisms, of a more or less controversial character, on this work, have appeared since the publication of the second edition ; and Dr. Whewell has lately published a reply to those parts of it in which some of his opinions were controverted.* 1 have carefully reconsidered all the points on an hieh my conclu- sions have been assailed ; but, I have not to announce a change of opinion on any matter of importance. Such minor oversights as have been detected, either by myself or by my critics, I have, in general silently, corrected ; but it is not to be inferred that I agree with the objections which have been made to a passage in every instance in which I have altered or cancelled it. I have often done so, merely that it might not remain a stumbling-block, when the amount of dis- cussion necessary to place the matter in its true light would have exceeded what was suitable to the occasion. To several of the arguments which have been urged against me, I have thought it useful to reply with some degree of minuteness ; not * Kow forming a cLajiter in his volume on The Philosophy of Di&covei~y. VI PREFACE. from any taste for controversy, but because the opportunity was favourable for placing my own conclusions, and the grounds of them, more clearly and completely before the reader. Truth on these sub- jects is militant, and can only establish itself by means of conflict. The most opposite opinions can make a plausible show of evidence while each has the statement of its own case ; and it is only possible to ascertain which of them is in the right after hearing and comparing what each can say against the other, and what the other can urge in its defence. Even the criticisms from which I most dissent have been of great service to me, by showing in what places the exposition most needed to be improved or the argument strengthened. And I should have been well pleased if the book had undergone a much greater amount of attack, as in that case I should probably have been enabled to improve it still more than I believe I have now done. PREFACE TO THE EIGHTH EDITION. In the subsequent editions, the attempt to improve the work by additions and corrections, suggested by criticism or by thought, has been continued. The additions and corrections in tlie present (eighth) edition, which are not very considerable, are chiefly such as have been suggested by Professor Bain's Logic, a book of great merit and value. Mr. Bain's view of the science is essentially the same with that taken in the present treatise, the differences of opinion being few and unimportant compared with the agreements ; and he has not only enriched the exposition by many applications and illustrative details, but has appended to it a minute and very valuable discussion of the logical principles specially applicable to each of the sciences ; a task for which the encyclopedical character of his knowledge peculiarly qualified him. I have in several instances made use of his exposition to improve my ow^n, by adopting, and occasionally by controverting, matter contained in his treatise. The longest of tlie additions belongs to the chapter on Causation, and is a discussion of the question, hoAV far, if at all, tlie ordinaiy mode of stating the law of Cause and Effect requires modification to adapt it to the new doctrine of the Conservation of Force : a point still more fully and elaborately treated in Mr. Bain's work. C 0 I^ T E N T S. INTHODUCTIOK c. A definition at the commencement of a subject must be provisional Is Logic the art and science of reasoning? Or the art and science of the pursuit of truth ? Logic is concerned with inferences, not with intuitive trutlis Relation of Logic to the otlier sciences . . Its utility, how shown Uefinitiuu of Logic stated and illustrated BOOK I. OF NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. Chapter I. I 0/ the Necessity of commencing with an \ Analysis of Languaye. BEC. PAGE 1. Theory of names, why a necessary | part of Ix»«ic ii ; 2. First step in the analysis of Pro- I positions . . .. . . . . 12 | 3. Names must be studied before i things 13 Chapter II. Of Names. 1. Names ore names of things, not of our ideas 2. Words which are not names, but pai ts of names 3. General and Singular names 4. Concrete and Abstract 5. Connotative and Non-counoiative 6. Positive and Negative 7. Relative and A b-olute 8. Univocal and ^Equivocal . . Chapter III. Of the Things denoted by Names. 1. Necessity of an enumeration of Nameable Things. The Cate- gories of Aristotle . . . . . . 29 2. Ambiguity of the most general names . . . . 30 3. Feelings, or states of consciousness 4. Feelings must be distinguislied from theii- physical antecedents. Perceptions, what, 5. Volitions and Actions, what 6. Substance and Atti ibute . . 7. Body . . 8. Mind 9. Qualities 10. Relations n. Resemblance.. 12. Quantity 13. All attributes of bodies are grounded on states of conscious- ness 14. So also all attributes of mind . . 15. Recapitulation PAGE 32 Chapter IV. Of Propositions. Nature and office of the copula . . 49 Affirmative and Negative proposi- tions 51 Simple and Complex . . . . 52 Universal, Particular, and Singular 54 Chapter V. Of the Import oj Propositions. I. Doctrine that a Proposition is the expression of a relation between two ideas 55 viii CONTENTS. Doctrine that it is the expression of a relation between the mean- ings of two names Doctrine that it consists in refer- ring Ronietbing to, or excluding something from, a class . . What it really is It asserts (or denies) a sequence, a co-existence, a simple existence, a causation — or a resemblance Propositions of which the terms are abstract 68 Chapter VI. Oj Propositions merely Verbal. 1. Essential and Accidental Proposi- tions 2. All essential Propositions are identical Propositions 3. Individuals have no essences 4. Real Propositions, how distin- guished from verbal 5. Two modes of representing the import of a real Proposition . . 7 Chapter VII. Of the Nature of Classification, and the Five Predicables. 1. Classification, how connected with naming 74 76 SEC. PAGE 2. The Predicables, what .. .. 77 3. Genus and Species . . . . . . 77 4. Kinds have a real existence in nature 79 5. Differentia , . 8i 6. Differentiai for general purposes, and differentiae for special or technical purposes . , . . 83 7. Proprium 84 8. Accidens 88 Chapter VIII. Of Definition. A definition, what 86 Every name can be defined whose meaning is susceptible of analy- sis 87 Complete, how distinguished from incomplete definitions . . . . 88 — and from descriptions . . . . 89 What are called definitions of Things, are definitions of Names with an implied assumption of tlie existence of Things corre- sponding to them 92 — even when such things do not in reality exist . . . . . . 97 Definitions, though of names only, must be grounded on knowledge of the corresponding things . . 98 BOOK II. OF EEASONING. Chapter I. Of Inference, or Reasoning, in general. 1. Retrospect of the preceding Book 103 2. Inferences improperly so called . . 104 3. Inferences proper, distinguished into inductions and ratiocina- tions 107 Chapter II. Of Batiocination, or Syllogism. 1. Analysis of the Syllogism .. .. 108 2. The dictum de omni not the foun- dation of reasoning, but a mere identical proposition .. .. 113 3. What is the really fundamental axiom of Ratiocination .. .. 116 4. The other form of the axiom . . 117 Chapter III. Of the Functions and Logical Value of the Syllogism. 1. Is the Syllogism a petitio prin- cipii? . . . . . . .... 119 2. InsufiBciency of the common theory 120 3. All inference is from particulars. to particulars 121 4. General Propositions are a record of such inferences, and the rules of the Syllogism are rules for the interpretation of the record . . 126 5. The Syllogism not the type of reasoning, but a test of it . . 128 6. The true type, what . . . . 131 7 Relation between Induction and Deduction .. .. .. .. 133 8. Objections answered .. .. 134 9. Of Formal Logic, and its relation to the Logic of Truth . . . . 136 CONTENTS. ht Chapter IV. 0/ Trains of Reasoning, and Deduc- tive Sciences. SEC PAGE 1. For what purpose trains of reason- ing exist 2. A train of reasoning is a series of inductive Inferences 3. — from particulars to particulars through marks of marks . . 4. Why there are deductive sciences 5. Why otlier sciences still remain expeiimental 6. Experimental sciences may become deductive by the progress of experiment 7. In what manner this usually takes place 137 138 139 141 143 M5 145 Chapter V. Of Demonstration, and Ifecessar^ Truths. The Theorems of Geometry are necessary truths i-uly in the sense of necessarily following from hypotheses Those liypotheses are real facts with some of their circumstances exaggerated or omitted . . Some of the first principles of Geometry are axioms, and these are not hypothetical — but are experimental truths . . An objection answered SEC. PAGE 6. Dr. Whewell's opinions on axioms examined . . 156 Chapter VI. The same Subject continued. 1. All deductive sciences are induc- tive 164 2. The propositions of the Science of Number are not verbal, but gene- ralisations from experience . . 166 3. In what sense hypothetical . . 169 4. The characteristic property of de- monstrative science is to be hypothetical .. .. .. 170 5. Definition of demonstrative evi- dence 171 Chapter VII. Examination of some Opinions op- posed to the preceding doctrines. 172 173 Doctrine of the Universal Pos- tulate . . The test of inconceivability does not represent the aggregate of past experience — nor is implied in every process of thought 175 Objections answered .. .. 179 Sir W. Hamilton's opinion on the Principles of Contradiction and Excluded Middle 182 BOOK III. OF INDUCTION. Chapter I. Preliminary Ohstrvations on Induc- tion in General. 1. Importance of an Inductive Logic 185 2. The Logic of Science is also that of business and life 185 Chapter II. Of Inductions im,properly so called. 1. Inductions distinguished from ver- bal transformations . . . . 18 2. — from inductions, falsely so called, in mathem-atics . . . . 19 3. — and from descriptions . . . . 19 4. Examination of Dr. Whewell's theory of Induction 5. Further illustration of the preced ing remarks 198 192 Chapter III. Od the G-round of Induction. Axiom of the uniformity of the course of Nature . . . . . . 200 Not true in every sense. Induc- tion per enumerationem simplicem 203 The question of Inductive Logic stated 20s Chapter IV. Of Laivs of Nature. The general regularity in nature is a tissue of partial regularities, called laws ao6 Scientific induction must be grounded on previous spon- tanei 'US inductions .. .. 208 Ate there any inductions fitted to be a test of all others ? . . . . 20Q CONTENTS. Chapter V. 0/ the Law of Univei'sal Causation. SEC. PAGE 1. The universal law of successive plieiioinena is the Law of Causation 211 2. — i.e. the law that every con- sequent has an invariable ante- cedent 213 3. The cause of a phenomenon is the assemblage of its conditions . . 214 4. The distinction of agent and patient illusory 218 5. Case in which the effect consists in giving a property to an object 220 6. Tlie c;iuse is not the invariai)le antecedent, but the uncondi- tional invavUMo antecedent .. 221 7. Can a cause be simultaneous with its effect? . . .. .. . . 224 8. Idea of a permanent Cause, or original natural agent . . . . 225 9. Uniformities of co-existence be- tween effects of different per- manent causes are not laws . . 227 10. Theory of the Conservation of Force 228 11. Doctrine that volition is an eflfi- cient cause, examined . . . . 232 Chapter VI. Of the Composition of Causes. 1. Two modes of , the conjunct action of causes, the mechanical and the chemical . . . . . . 242 2. The composition of causes the general rule, the other case ex- ct-ptional 244 3. Are effects jji oportional to their causes ? . . 246 Chapter VII. bf Observation and Experiment. 1, The first step of inductive inquiry is a mental analysis of conqolex phenottiena into thuir elements 247 2. The next is an actual separation 249 of those elements . . 3. Advantages of experiment over observation 1 '. 249 4. Advantages of observation over experiment 25 Chapter VIII. Of the Four Methods of Experimental Inquiry. 1. Method of Agreement . . . . 253 2. M'-thod of Difference ,. .. 255 3. Mutual relation of these two me- thods 256 SEC. PAGE 4. Joint Method of Agreement and Difference . . . » . , . . 258 5. Method of Residues 259 6. Method of Concomitant Variations 260 7. Limitations of this last method . . 264 Chapter IX. Miscellaneous Examples of the Four Methods. 1. Liebig's theory of metallic poisons 267 2. Theory of induced electricity . . 269 3. Dr. Wells' theory of dew .. .. 271 4. Dr. Brown-Sequard's theory of cadaveric rigidity 276 5. Examplesof the Method of Residues 279 6. Di-. Whewell's objections to the Four Methods 282 Chapter X. Of Plurality of Causes : and of the In- termixture of Effects. 1. One effect may have several causes 285 2. — which is the source of a character- istic imperfection of the Method of Agreement 286 3. Plurality of Causes, how ascer- tained 288 4. Concurrence of Causes which do not compound their effects . . 289 5. Difficulties of the investigation when causes compound their effects . . . . . . . . . . 291 6. Three modes of investigating the laws of complex effects . . . . 294 7. The method of simple observation inapplicable 295 8. The purely experimental method inapplicable 296 Chapter XI. Of the Deductive Method. 1. First stage ; ascertainment of the liiws of the separate causes by direct inductijan 299 2. Sec! >nd stage ; ratiocination from the simple laws of the complex cases . . . . . . . . . . 302 3. Third stage ; verification by specific experience 303 Chapter XII. Of the Explanation of Laws of Nature. 1. Explanation defined . . . . 305 2. First mode of explanation ; by re- solvinsr the law of a complex effect into the laws of tlie concurrent causes and the fact of their co-ex- istence 305 CONTENTS. TO. BEC. PAGE 3. Second mode ; by the detection of an intei-mediate link in the se- quence 306 4. Liiws are always resolved into laws more general than themselves .. 307 5. Third mode ; the subsiimption of less general laws under a more general one . . 308 6. What the explanation of a law of nature amounts to 310 Chapter XIII. Miscellaneous Examples of the Explana- tion of Laics of Nature. 1. The general theories of the sciences 311 2. Examples from chemical specula- tions 312 3. Example from Dr. Brown-Seqnard's researches on the nervous systcTu 313 4. Examples of following newly-dis- covered laws into their complex mjinifestations 314 5. Examples of empirical generalisa- tions, afterwards confirmed and explained deductively .. .. 315 6. Example from mental science . . 316 7. Tendency of all the sciences to be- come deductive 317 Chapter xrv. Of the Limits to the Explanation of Laws of Nature ; and of Hypotheses. 1. Can all the seqxiences in nature be resolvable into one law? . . . . 318 2. Ultimate laws cannot be less numer- ous than the distinguishable feel- ings of o\ir nature 318 3. In what sense ultimate facts can be explained .. 321 4. The proper use of scientific hypo- theses . . . . 322 5. Tiieir indispensableness . . . . 326 6. The two degrees of legitimacy in hypotheses 327 7. Some inquiries apparently hypo- thetical are really inductive .. 332 Chapter XV. Of Progressive Effects ; and of the Con- tinued Action of Causes. 1. How a progressive effect results from the simple continuance of the cause 333 2. — and from the progressiveness of the cause 336 3. Derivative laws generated from a single ultimate law 337 Chapter XVI. Of Empirical Laws. 1. Definition of an emi-irical law .. 338 SEC. PACK 2. Derivative laws commonly depend on collocations 339 3. The collocations of the permanent causes are not reducible to any law 340 4. Hence empirical laws cannot be relied on beyond the limits of actual experience . . . . . . 340 5. Generalisations which rest only 011 the Method of Agreement can 01. ly be received as empirical laws . . 341 6. Signs from which an observed uni- fonnity of sequence may be pre- sumed to be resolvable . . . . 342 7. Two kinds of empirical laws . . 343 Chapter XVII. Of Chance and its Elimination. 1. The proof of empirical laws de- pends on tiie theory of chance . . 344 2. Cliance defined and characterised 345 3. The elimination of chance . . . . 348 4. Discovery of residual phenomena by eliminating chance .. .. 349 5. The doctrine of chances .. .. 350 Chapter XVIII. Of the Calculation of Chances. 1. Foundation of the doctrine of chances, as taught by mathe- matics.. .•. ■.. .. .. 350 2. The doctrine tenable .. .. 352 3. On what foundation it really rests 352 4. Its tiltimate dependence on causa- tion 355 5. Theorem of the doctrine of chances which relates to the cause of a given event 357 6. How applicable to the elimination of chance 358 Chapter XIX. Of the Extension of Derivative Laws to Adjacent Cases. 1. Derivative laws, when not causal, are almost always contingent on collocations . . 360 2. On what grounds they can be ex- tended to cases Ijej'ond the bounds of actual experience . . . . 361 3. Those cases must be adjacent cases 362 Chapter XX. Of Analogy. 1. Various senses of the word analogy 364 2. Nature of analogical evidence . . 365 3. On what circumstances its value depends 367 3ui CONTENTS. Chapter XXI. Of the Evidence of the Law of Universal Causation. SKC. PAGE 1. The law of causality does not rest on an instinct 368 2. But on an induction by simple enumeration 371 3. In what cases such induction is allowable 373 4. The universal prevalence of the law of causality, on what grounds ad- missible 374 Chapter XXII. Of Uniformities of Co-existence not de- pendent on Causation. 377 379 380 381 382 382 383 384 1. Uniformities of co-existence which result from laws of sequence 2. The pro()erties of Kinds are uni formities of co-existence . . 3. Some are derivative, others ulti mate 4. No universal axiom of co-existence 5. The evidence of uniformities of co- existence, how measured . . 6. When derivative, their evidence is that of empirical laws 7. So also when ultimate 8. Ttie evidence stronger in propor- tion as tiie law is more general . . 9. Every distinct Kind must be exa- mined 385 Chapter XXIII. Of Approximate Genei'alisations, and Probable Evidence. 1. The inferences called probable rest on approximate generalisations. . 386 2. Approximate generalisations less usef id in science than in life . . 387 3. In what cases they may be resoi-ted to 388 4. In what manner proved . . . . 389 5. With what precautions employed 390 SEC. pagb 6. The two modes of combining pro- babilities 391 7. How approximate generalisations may be converted into accurate generalisations equivalent to them 394 Chapter XXIV. Of the Remaining Laws of Nature. 1. Propositions which assert mere ex- istence 2,gs 2. Resemblance considered as a sub- ject of science 3. The axioms and theorems of mathe- matics comprise the principal laws of resemblance 4. — and those of order in place, and rest on induction by simple enu- meration 5. The propositions of arithmetic aflSrm the modes of formation of some given number 6. Those of algebra affirm the equiva- lence of different modes of forma- tion of numbei's generally 7. The propositions of Geometry are laws of outward nature . . 8. Why Geometry is almost entirely deductive 9. Function of mathematical truths in the other sciences, and limits of that function Chapter XXV. Of the Grounds of Disbelief. 1. Improbability and impossibility . . 2. Examination of Hume's doctrine of miracles 3. The degrees of improbability corre- spond to differences in the nature of the generalisation with which an assertion conflicts 4. A fact is not incredible because the chances are against it 5. Are coincidences less credible than other facts? 6. An opinion of Laplace examined . . 396 397 398 405 406 407 408 413 415 BOOK IV. OF OPERATIONS SUBSIDIARY TO INDUCTION. Chapter I. Of Observation and Description. I. Observation, how far a subject of Logic .. .. .. .. .. 419 a. A great part of what seems obser- vation iti really inference . . . . 420 The description of an observation affirms more than is contained in the observation 422 — namely, an agreement among phenomena ; and the comparison of phenomena to ascertain such agreements is a preliminary to induction 423 CONTENTS. Xlll Chapter II. Of Abstraction, or the Formation of Conceptions. SEC. PAGE 1. The comparison which is a prelimi- nary to induction implies general conceptions 424 2. — but these need not be pre-exis- tent 425 3. A general conception, originally tho result of a comparison, becomes itself the type of comparison . . 427 4. What is meant by appropriate con- ceptions . . . . . . , . 429 5. — and by clear conceptions . . 430 6. Further illustration of the subject 432 Chapter III. Of Naming, as subsidiary to Induction. 1. The fundamental property of names as an insiriiment of thought .. 433 2. Names are not indispensable to in- duction 434 3. In what manner subservient to it 435 4. General names not a mere contriv- ance to economise the use of lan- guage 436 Chapter IV. Of the Requisites of a Philosophical Language, and the Principles of De- finition. 1. First requisite of philosophical lan- guage, a steady and determinate I meaning for every general name 436 2. Names in common use have often a loose connotation . . . . 436 3. — wliich the logician should fix, with as little alteration as pes- j sible 438 I 4. Vihy definition is often a question not of words but of things . . 439 5. How the logician should deal with the transitive applications of WO! ds . . . . . . . . . . 441 6. Evil consequences of casting off any portion of the customary connota- tion of words Chapter V. 444 On the Natural History of the VaHa- tions in the Meaning of Terms. I. How circumstances originally acci- dental become incorporated into the meaning of words . . . . 448 SEC. PAGE 2. — and sometimes become the whole meaning .. 450 3. Tendency of words to become gene- ralised .. .. 451 4. — and to become specialised . . 453 Chapter VI. The Principles of Philosophical Lan- guage further considered. 1. Second requisite of philosophical language, a name far every im- portant meaning 455 2. — viz. first, an accurate descrip- tive terminology 456 3. — secondly, a name for each of the more important results of scien- tific abstraction 458 4. — thirdly, a nomenclature, or sys- tem of the names of Kinds . . 459 5. Peculiar nature of the connotation of names which belong to a nomen- clature 461 6. In what cases language may, and may not, be used lucchauically . . 462 Chapter VII. Of Classification as Subsidiary to In- duction. 1. Classification as here treated of, wherein different from the classi- fication implied in naming . . 465 2. Theory of natural groups . . . . 466 3. Are natural groups given by type or by definition? 468 4. Kinds are natural groups .. .. 470 5. How the names of Kinds should be constructed 473 Chapter VIII. Of Classification by Series. 1. Natural groups should be arranged in a natural series . . . . . . 475 2. The arrangement should follow the degrees of the main phenome- non 475 3. — which implies the assumption of a type-species . . . . . . 476 4. How the divisions of the series should be determined . . . . 477 5. Zoology affords the completest type of scientific classification.. .. 478 XIV CONTENTS. BOOK V. ON FALLACIES. 485 487 Chapter I. Of Fallacies in General. SEC. PAGE 1. Theory of fallacies a necessary part of Logic 481 2. Casual mistakes are not fallacies. . 482 3. The moral sources of erroneous opinion, how related to the intel- lectual 482 Chapter II. Classification of Fallacies. 1. On what criteria a classification of fallacies should be grounded 2. The five classes of fallacies. . 3. The reference of a fallacy to one or another class is sometimes arbi- trary Chapter III. Fallacies of Simple Inspection, or a priori Fallacies. 1. Character of this class of Fallacies 48! 2. Natural prejudice of mistaking subjective laws for objective, exemplified in popular supersti- tions 48c 3. Natural prejudices that things which we think of together must exist together, and that what is inconceivable must be false 4. Natural prejudice of ascribing objective existence to abstrac- tions 5. Fallacy of the Sufficient Reason . . 6. Natural prejudice that tiie differ- ences in nature correspond to the distinctions in language .. 7. Prejudice that a phenomenon can- not liave more than one cause , . 8. Prejudice that the conditions of a • phenomenon must resemble the phenomenon 491 495 496 497 Chapter IV. Fallacies of Observation. SEC. PAGE 1. Non-observation and Mal-observa- tion 2. Non-observation of instances, and non-obseryation of circumstances 3. Examples of the former 4. — and of the latter . . 5. Mal-observation characterised and exemplified Chapter V. Fallacies of Generalisation. 1. Character of the class 2. Certain kinds of generaHsation must always be groundless 3. Attempts to resolve phenomena radically different into the same 4. Fallacy of mistaking empirical for causal laws . . 5. Post hoc, ergo propter hoc ; and the deductive fallacy corresponding to it 6. Fallacy of False Analogies . . 7. Function of metaphors in reason- ing 8. How fallacies of generalisation grow out of bad classification . . Chapter VI. Fallacies of Ratiocination, 1. Introductory Remarks 2. Fallacies in the conversion and pequipollency of propositions 4- Fallacies in the syllogistic process Fallacy of changing the premises . . Chapter VII. Fallacies of Confusion. 1. Fallacy of Ambiguous Terms 2. Fallacy of Petitio Principii 3. Fallacy of Ignoratio EUnchi 506 506 507 509 512 S14 515 516 519 520 525 526 526 527 527 530 537 542 CONTENTS. BOOK VI. ON THE LOGIC OF THE MOEAL SCIENCES. Chapter I. Introductory Remarks, SEG. PAGE I. The backward sfcite of the Moial Sciences can only be remedied by applying to them the methods of Physical Science, duly ex- tended and genei-alisod . . . . 545 3. How far this can be attemi^ted in the present work 546 Chapter II. Of Liberty and Xecessity. 1. Are human actions subject to the law of causality ? 547 2. The doctrine commonly called Philosophical Necessity, in what sense true 547 3. Inappropriateness and pernicious effect of the term Necessity . . 549 4. A motive nob always the antici- pation of a pleasure or u pain . . 551 Chapter III. That there is, or may be, a Science of Human Nature. 1. There may be sciences which are not exact sciences 552 2. To what scientific type the Science of Human Nature corresponds . . 553 Chapter IV. Of the Laics of Mind. What is meant by Laws of Mind. , Is there a Science of Psychology ? The principal investigations of Psychology characterised Relation of nienttd facts to physi- cal conditions 555 555 557 Chapter V. Of Ethology, or the Science of the For- mation of Character. 1. The Empirical Laws of Human Nature 562 2. — are merely approximate genera- lisations. The universal laws are those of the formation of character . , 563 3. The laws of the formation of char- acter cannot be ascertained by obNcrvation and experiment .. 564 4. — but must be studied deductively 567 5. The principles of Ethology are the axiomata media of mental science 568 6. Ethology characterised . • . . 570 Chapter VI. General Considerations on the Social Science. 1. Are Social Phenomena a subject of Science? .. 571 2. Of what nature the Social Science must be 572 Chapter VII. Of the Chemical, or Experimental Method in the Social Science. 1. Characters of the mode of thinking which deduces political doctrines from specific experience . . , . 573 2. In ttie Social Science experiments are impossible . . . . . . 574 3. — the Method of Difference in- ajjplicable 575 4. — and the Methods of Agreement and of Concomitant Variations inconclusive .. .. ., 576 5. The Method of Residues also in- conclusive, and presupposes De- duction 577 Chapter VIII. Of the Geometrical, or Abstract Method. I. Characters of this mode of think- of the Geometrical the ing 2. Examples Method 3. The interest-philosoi^hy of Bentham School . . 578 579 580 Chapter IX. Of the Physical, or Concrete Deductive Method. 1. The Direct and Inverse Deductive Metlinds 583 2. Difficulties of the Direct Deductive ilethod in the Social Science . . 585 3. To wliat extent the ditferent branches of sociolo„dcal specu- XVI CONTENTS. SIC. PAGE lation can be studied apart. Political Economy characterised 587 4. Political Ethology, or the science of National Character , . . . 590 5. The Empirical Laws of the Social Science . . 592 6. The Verification of the Social Science 593 Chapter X. Oj the Inverse Deductive, or His- torical Method. 1. Distinction between the general Science of Society and special Sociological inquiries . . . . 594 2. What is meant by a State of Society? 595 3. The Progressiveness of Man and Society 595 4. The laws of the succession of states of Society can only be ascei-- tained by the Inverse Deductive Method 597 5. Social Statics, or the science of the Co-existences of Social Pheno- mena .. 598 6. Social Dynamics, or the science of the Successions of Social Pheno- mena . . 603 7. Outlines of the Historical Method 604 8. Fiiture prospects of Sociological Inquiry .. 605 Chapter XL Additional Elucidations of the Science of History. SKC. PAGE 1. The subjection of historical facts to tuiiform laws is verified by statistics 607 2. — does not imply the insignifi- cance of moral causes . . . . 6og 3. — nor the inefficacy of the charac- ters of individuals and of the acts of governments .. .. 611 4. The historical importance of emi- nent men and of the policy of governments illustrated . . . . 613 Chapter XII. Of the Logic of Practice, or Art ; in- cluding Morality and Policy. 1. Morality not a science, but an Art 616 2. Relation between rules of Art and the theorems of the correspond- ing science 616 3. Wliat is the proper function of rules of Art? 617 4. Art cannot be Deductive . . . . 618 5. Every Art consists of truths of Science, arranged in the order suitable for some practical use . . 619 6. Teleology, or the doctrine of Ends 619 7. Necessity of an ultimate standard, or first principle of Teleology . . 620 8. Conclusion 622 INTRODUCTION § I. There is as great diversity among authors in the modes which they have adopted of defining logic, as in their treatment of the details of it. This is what might naturally be expected on any subject on which writers have availed themselves of the same language as a means of de- livering different ideas. Ethics and jurisprudence are liable to the remark in common with logic. Almost every writer having taken a different view of some of the particulars which these branches of knowledge are usually understood to include, each has so framed his definition as to indicate beforehand his own peculiar tenets, and sometimes to beg the question in their favour. This diversity is not so much an evil to be complained of, as an inevit- able and in some degree a proper result of the imperfect state of those sciences. It is not to be expected that there should be agreement about the definition of anything, until there is agreement about the thing itself. To define, is to select from among all the properties of a thing, those which shall be understood to be designated and declared by its name ; and the properties must be well known to us before we can be competent to deter- mine which of them are fittest to be chosen for this purpose. Accordingly, in the case of so complex an aggrega- tion of particulars as are compre- hended in anything which can be called a science, the definition we set out with is seldom that which a more extensive knowledge of the subject ' shows to be the most appropriate. Until we know the particulars them- I selves, we cannot fix upon the most correct and compact mode of circum- scribing them by a general descrip- tion. It was not until after an ex- tensive and accurate acquaintance with the details of chemical pheno- mena, that it was found possible to frame a rational definition of chemis- try ; and the definition of the science of life and organization is still a matter of dispute. So long as the sciences are imperfect, the definitions must partake of their imperfection ; and if the former are progressive, the latter ought to be so too. As much, therefore, as is to be expected from a definition placed at the commence- ment of a subject, is that it should define the scope of our inquiries : and the definition which I am about to offer of the science of logic, pretends to nothing more, than to be a state- ment of the question which I have put to myself, and which this book is an attempt to resolve. The reader is at liberty to object to it as a defini- tion of logic ; but it is at all events a correct definition of the subject of these volumes. § 2. Logic has often been called the Art of Reasoning. A writer* who has done more than any other person to restore this study to the rank from which it had fallen in the estimation of the cultivated class in our own country, has adopted the * Archbishop Whately. A INTRODUCTION. above definition with an amendment ; he has defined Logic to be the Science, as well as the Art, of reasoning ; meaning by the former term, the analysis of the mental process which takes place whenever we reason, and by the latter, the rules, grounded on that analysis, for conducting the pro- cess correctly. There can be no doubt as to the propriety of the emen- dation. A right understanding of the mental process itself, of the con- ditions it depends on, and the steps of which it consists, is the only basis on which a system of rules, fitted for the direction of the process, can pos- sibly be founded. Art necessarily presupposes knowledge ; art, in any but its infant state, presupposes scien- tific knowledge : and if every art does not bear the name of a science, it is only because several sciences are often necessary to form the ground- work of a single art. So complicated are the conditions which govern our practical agency, that to enable one thing to be done, it is often requisite to know the nature and properties of many things. Logic, then, comprises the science of reasoning, as well as an art, founded on that science. But the word Reason- ing, again, like most other scientific terms in popular use, abounds in ambiguities. In one of its accepta- tions, it means syllogizing ; or the mode of inference which may be called (with sufficient accuracy for the present purpose) concluding from generals to particulars. In another of its senses, to reason is simply to infer any assertion, from assertions already admitted : and in this sense induction is as much entitled to be called reasoning as the demonstra- tions of geometry. Writers on logic have generally preferred the former acceptation of the term : the latter, and more exten- sive signification is that in which I mean to use it. I do this by virtue of the right I claim for every author, to give whatever provisional definition he pleases of his own subject. But sufficient reasons will, I believe, un- fold themselves as we advance, why this should be not only the provisional but the final definition. It involves, at all events, no arbitrary change in the meaning of the word ; for, with the general usage of the English language, the wider signification, I believe, accords better than the more restricted one. § 3. But Reasoning, even in the widest sense of which the word is susceptible, does not seem to compre- hend all that is included, either in the best, or even in the most current, conception of the scope and province of our science. The employment of the word Logic to denote the theory of Argumentation, is derived from the Aristotelian, or, as they are commonly termed, the scholastic, logicians. Yet even with them, in their systematic treatises. Argumentation was the sub- ject only of the third part : the two former treated of Terms, and of Pro- positions ; under one or other of which heads were also included Definition and Division. By some, indeed, these previous topics were professedly intro- duced only on account of their con- nexion with reasoning, and as a preparation for the doctrine and rules of the syllogism. Yet they were treated with greater minuteness, and dwelt on at greater length, than was required for that purpose alone. More recent writers on logic have generally understood the term as it was em- ployed by the able author of the Port Royal Logic ; viz., as equivalent to the Art of Thinking. Nor is this acceptation confined to books, and scientific inquiries. Even in ordinary conversation, the ideas connected with the word Logic include at least pre- cision of language, and accuracy of classification : and we perhaps oftener hear persons speak of a logical ar- rangement, or of expressions logically defined, than of conclusions logically deduced from premises. Again, a man is often called a great logician, or a man of powerful logic, not for DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC. the accuracy of his deductions, but for the extent of his command over premises ; because the general propo- sitions required for explaining a difl&- culty or refuting a sophism, copiously and promptly occur to him : because, in short, his knowledge, besides being ample, is well under his command for argumentative use. Whether, there- fore, we conform to the practice of those who have made the subject their particular study, or to that of popular writers and common dis- course, the province of logic will include several operations of the intel- lect not usually considered to fall within the meaning of the terms Reasoning and Argumentation. These various operations might be brought within the compass of the science, and the additional advantage be obtained of a very simple defini- tion, if, by an extension of the term, sanctioned by high authorities, we were to define logic as the science which treats of the operations of the human understanding in the pursuit of truth. For to this ultimate end, naming, classification, definition, and all other operations over which logic has ever claimed jurisdiction, are essentially subsidiary. They may all be regarded as contrivances for enabling a person to know the truths which are needful to him, and to know them at the precise moment at which they are needful. Other pur- poses, indeed, are also served by these operations ; for instance, that of im- parting our knowledge to others. But, viewed with regard to this pur- pose, they have never been considered as within the province of the logician. The sole object of Logic is the guid- ance of one's own thoughts : the communication of those thoughts to others falls under the consideration of Rhetoric, in the large sense in which that art was conceived by the ancients ; or of the still more exten- sive art of Education. Logic takes cognizance of our intellectual opera- tions, only as they conduce to our over that knowledge for our own uses. If there were but one rational being in the universe, that being might be a perfect logician ; and the science and art of logic would be the same for that one person as for the whole human race. § 4. But, if the definition which wo formerly examined included too little, that which is now suggested has the opposite fault of including too much. Truths are known to us in two ways : some are known directly, and of themselves ; some through the medium of other truths. The former are the subject of Intuition, or Con- sciousness ; * the latter, of Inference. The truths known by intuition are the original premises from which all others are inferred. Our assent to the conclusion being grounded on the truth of the premises, we never could arrive at any knowledge by reason- ing, unless something could be known antecedently to all reasoning. Examples of truths known to us by immediate consciousness, are our own bodily sensations and mental feelings. I know directly, and of my own know- ledge, that I was vexed yesterday, or that I am hungry to-day. Ex- amples of truths which we know only by way of inference, are occurrences which took place while we were absent, the events recorded in history, or the theorems of mathematics. The two former we infer from the testi- mony adduced, or from the traces of those past occurrences which still exist ; the latter, from the premises laid down in books of geometry, under the title of definitions and axioms. Whatever we are capable of knowing must belong to the one class or to * I use these terms indiscriminately, be- cause, for the purpose in view, there is no need for making any distinction between tliem. But metapliysicians usually re- strict the name Intuition to the direct knowledge we are supposed to have of things external to our minds, and Con- sciousness to our knowledge of our own mental phenomena. INTRODUCTION. the other ; must be in the number of the primitive data, or of the conclu- sions which can be drawn from these. With the original data, or ultimate premises of our knowledge; with their number or nature, the mode in which they are obtained, or the tests by which they may be distinguished ; logic, in a direct way at least, has, in the sense in which I conceive the science, nothing to do. These ques- tions are partly not a subject of science at all, partly that of a very different science. Whatever is knovvTi to us by con- sciousness, is known beyond possibility of question. What one sees or feels, whether bodily or mentally, one can- not but be sure that one sees or feels. No science is required for the purpose of establishing such truths ; no rules of art can render our knowledge of them more certain than it is in itself. There is no logic for this portion of our knowledge. But we may fancy that we see or feel what we in reality infer. A truth, or supposed truth, which is really the result of a very rapid in- ference, may seem to be apprehended intuitively. It has long been agreed by thinkers of the most opposite schools, that this mistake is actually made in so familiar an instance as that of the eyesight. There is nothing of which we appear to ourselves to be more directly conscious, than the distance of an object from us. Yet it has long been ascertained, that what is perceived by the eye, is at most nothing more than a variously coloured surface ; that when we fancy we see distance, all we really see is certain variations of apparent size, and de- grees of faintness of colour ; that our estimate of the object's distance from us is the result partly of a rapid in- ference from the muscular sensations accompanying the adjustment of the focal distance of the eye to objects unequally remote from us, and partly of a comparison (made with so much rapidity that we are unconscious of :piaking it) between the size and colour of the object as they appear at the time, and the size and colour of the same or of similar objects as they ap- peared when close at hand, or when their degree of remoteness was known by other evidence. The perception of distance by the eye, which seems so like intuition, is thus, in reality, an inference grounded on experience ; an inference, too, which we learn to make ; and which we make with more and more correctness as our experi- ence increases ; though in familiar cases it takes place so rapidly as to appear exactly on a par with those perceptions of sight which are really intuitive, our pex'ceptions of colour.* Of the science, therefore, which expounds the operations of the human understanding in the pursuit of truth, one essential part is the inquiry : What are the facts which are the objects of intuition or consciousness, and what are these which we merely infer? But this inquiry has never been considered a portion of logic. Its place is in another and a perfectly distinct department of science, to which the name metaphysics more particularly belongs : that portion of mental philosophy which attempts to determine what part of the furniture of the mind belongs to it originally, and what part is constructed out of materials furnished to it from without. To this science appertain the great and much debated questions of the existence of matter ; the existence of spirit, and of a distinction between it and matter ; the reality of time and space, as things without the mind, and distinguishable from the objects which are said to exist in them. For in the present state of the discussion * This important theory has of late been called in question by a writer of deserved reputation, Mr. Samuel Bailey; but I do not conceive that the grounds on which it has been admitted as an established doctrine for a century past, have been at all shaken by that gentleman's objections. I have elsewhere said what appeared to, me necessary in reply to his arguments. (Westminster Review for October 1842; re- printed iu Dissertations and Discussions^ vol, a.) t)EFINlTlON AND l^ROVINCE OF LOGIC.^ on these topics, it is almost univer- sally allowed that the existence of matter or of spirit, of space or of time, is in its nature unsusceptible of being proved ; and that if anything is known of them, it must be by imme- diate intuition. To the same science belong the inquiiries into the nature of Conception, Perception, Memory, and Belief ; all of which are opera- tions of the understanding in the pursuit of truth ; but with which, as phenomena of the mind, or with the possibility which may or may not exist of analysing any of them into simpler phenomena, the logician as such has no concern. To this science must also be referred the following, and all analogous questions : To what extent our intellectual faculties and our emotions are innate — to what extent the result of association : Whether God, and duty, are realities, the existence of which is manifest to us cl 2^riori by the constitution of our rational faculty ; or whether our ideas of them are acquired notions, the origin of which we are able to trace and explain ; and the reality of the objects themselves a question not of consciousness or intuition, but of evidence and reasoning. The province of logic must be re- stricted to that portion of our know- ledge which consists of inferences from truths previously known ; whether those antecedent data be general pro- positions, or particular observations and perceptions. Logic is not the science of Belief, but the science of Proof, or Evidence. In so far as belief professes to be founded on proof, the office of logic is to supply a test for ascertaining whether or not the belief is well grounded. With the claims which any proposition has to belief on the evidence of conscious- ness, that is, without evidence in tlie proper sense of the word, logic has nothing to do. § 5. By far the greatest portion of our knowledge, whether of general truths or of particular facts, being avowedly matter of inference, nearly the whole, not only of science, but of human conduct, is amenable to the authority of logic. To draw infer- ences has been said to be the great business of life. Every one has daily, hourly, and momentary need of ascer- taining facts which he has not directly observed ; not from any general pur- pose of adding to his stock of know- ledge, but because the facts them- selves are of importance to his in- terests or to his occupations. The business of the magistrate, of the military commander, of the navigator, of the physician, of the agriculturist, is merely to judge of evidence, and to act accordingly. They all have to ascertain certain facts, in order that they may afterwards apply certain rules, either devised by themselves, or prescribed for their guidance by others ; and as they do this well or ill, so they discharge well or ill the duties of their several callings. It is the only occupation in which the mind never ceases to be engaged ; and is the subject, not of logic, but of knowledge in general. Logic, however, is not the same thing with knowledge, though the field of logic is coextensive with the field of knowledge. Logic is the common judge and arbiter of all par- ticular investigations. It does not undertake to find evidence, but to determine whether it has been found. Logic neither observes, nor invents, nor discovers ; but judges. It is no part of the business of logic to infox'm the surgeon what appearances are found to accompany a violent death. This he must learn from his own experience and observation, or from that of others, his predecessors in his peculiar pursuit. But logic sits in judgment on the sufficiency of that observation and experience to justify his rules, and on the sufficiency of his rules to justify his conduct. It does not give him proofs, but teaches him what makes them proofs, and how he is to judge of them. It does not teach that any particular fact proves INTtlODtJCTION; any other, but points out to what conditions all facts must conform, in order that they may prove other facts. To decide whether any given fact fulfils these conditions, or whether facts can be found which fulfil them in a given case, belongs exclusively to the particular art or science, or to our knowledge of the particular subject. It is in this sense that logic is, what it was so expressively called by the schoolmen and by Bacon, ai's art mm ; the science of science itself. All science consists of data and conclu- sions from those data, of proofs and what they prove : now logic points out what relations must subsist be- tween data and whatever can be concluded from them, between proof and everything which it can prove. If there be any such indispensable relations, and if these can be precisely determined, every particular branch of science, as well as every individual in the guidance of his conduct, is bound to conform to those relations, under the penalty of making false inferences — of drawing conclusions which are not grounded in the reali- ties of things. Whatever has at any time been concluded justly, whatever knowledge has been acquired other- wise than by immediate intuition, depended on the observance of the laws which it is the province of logic to investigate. If the conclusions are just, and the knowledge real, those laws, whether known or not, have been observed. ' § 6. We need not, therefore, seek any farther for a solution of the question, so often agitated, respecting the utility of logic. If a science of logic exists, or is capable of existing, it must be useful. If there be rules to which every mind consciously or ■Unconsciously conforms in every in- stance in which it infers rightly, there seems little necessity for discussing whether a person is more likely to observe those rules, when he knows the rules, than when he is unac- c^uainted with them. A science inay undoulotedly bd brought to a certain, not inconsider- able, stage of advancement, without the application of any other logic to it than what all persons, who are said to have a sound xinderstanding, acquire empirically in the course of their studies. Mankind judged of evidence, and often correctly, before logic was a science, or they never could have made it one. And they executed great mechanical works be- fore they understood the laws of mechanics. But there are limits both, to what mechanicians can do without; principles of mechanics, and to what thinkers can do without principles of logic. A few individuals, by extra- ordinary genius, or by the accidental acquisition of a good set of intellec- tual habits, may work without prin- ciples in the same way, or nearly the same way, in which they would have worked if they had been in possession of principles. But the bulk of man- kind require either to understand the theory of what they are doing, or to have rules laid down for them by those who have understood the theory. In the progress of science from its easiest to its more difficult problems, each great step in advance has usually had either as its precursor, or as its accompaniment and necessary condi- tion, a corresponding improvement in the notions and principles of logic received among the most advanced thinkers. And if several of the more difficult sciences are still in so defec- tive a state ; if not only so little is proved, but disputation has not ter- minated even about the little which seemed to be so ; the reason perhaps is, that men's logical notions have not yet acquired the degree of extension, or of accuracy, requisite for the esti- mation of the evidence proper to those particular departments of knowledge. § 7. Logic, then, is the science of the operations of the understanding which are subservient to the estima- tion of evidence : both the process itself of advancing from known truths DEFINITION AND PROVINCE OF LOGIC. to unknown, and all other intellectual operations in so far as auxiliary to this. It includes, therefore, the opera- tion of Naming ; for language is an instrument of thought, as well as a means of communicating our thoughts. It includes, also, Definition, and Classification. For, the use of these operations {putting all other minds than one's own out of consideration) is to serve not only for keeping our evidences and the conclusions from them permanent and readily acces- sible in the memory, but for so mar- shalling the facts which we may at •any time be engaged in investigat- ing, as to enable us to perceive more •clearly what evidence there is, and to judge with fewer chances of error whether it be sufficient. These, there- fore, are operations specially instru- mental to the estimation of evidence, and, as such, are within the province of Logic. There are other more elementary processes, concerned in all thinking, such as Conception, Memory, and the like ; but of these it is not necessary that Logic should take any peculiar cognizance, since they have no special connexion with the problem of Evidence, further than that, like all other problems addressed to the understanding, it presupposes them. Our object, then, will be, to attempt a correct analysis of the intellectual process called Reasoning or Inference, and of such other mental operations as are intended to facilitate this : as well as, on the foundation of this analysis, and pari passu with it, to bring together or frame a set of rules or canons for testing the sufficiency of any given evidence to prove any given proposition. With respect to the first part of this undertaking, I do not attempt to decompose the mental operations in question into their ultimate elements. It is enough if the analysis as far as it goes is correct, and if it goes far enough for the practical purposes of logic considered as an art. The separation of a complicated pheno- menon into its component parts is not like a connected and interdependent chain of proof. If one link of an argument breaks, the whole drops to the ground ; but one step towards an analysis holds good and has an inde- pendent value, though we should never be able to make a second. The results which have been obtained by analytical chemistry are not the less valuable, though it should be dis- covered that all which we now call simple substances are really com- pounds. All other things are at any rate compounded of those elements : whether the elements themselves ad- mit of decomposition, is an important inquiry, but does not affect the cer- tainty of the science up to that point. I shall, accordingly, attempt to analyse the process of inference, and the processes subordinate to inference, so far only as may be requisite for as- certaining the difference between a correct and an incorrect performance of those processes. The reason for thus limiting our design, is evident. It has been said by objectors to logic, that we do not learn to use our muscles by studying their anatomy. The fact is not quite fairly stated ; for if the action of any of our muscles were vitiated by local weakness, or other physical defect, a knowledge of their anatomy might be very neces- sary for effecting a cure. But we should be justly liable to the criticism involved in this objection, were we, in a treatise on logic, to carry the analysis of the reasoning process be- yond the point at which any inac- curacy which may have crept into it must become visible. In learning bodily exercises (to carry on the same illustration) we do, and must, analyse the bodily motions so far as is neces- sary for distinguishing those which ought to be performed from those which ought not. To a similar extent, and no further, it is necessary that the logician should analyse the men- tal processes with which logic is con- cerned. Logic has no interest in carrying the analysis beyond the point at which it becomes apparent whether 8 INTRODUCTION. the operations have in any individual case been rightly or wrongly per- formed : in the same manner as the science of music teaches us to dis- criminate between musical notes, and to know the combinations of which they are susceptible, but not what number of vibrations in a second cor- respond to each ; which, though use- ful to be known, is useful for totally different purposes. The extension of Logic as a Science is determined by its necessities as an Art : whatever it does not need for its practical ends, it leaves to the larger science which may be said to correspond, not to any particular art, but to art in gene- ral ; the science which deals with the constitution of the human faculties ; and to which, in the part of our men- tal nature which concerns Logic, as well as in all other parts, it belongs to decide what are ultimate facts, and what are resolvable into other facts. And I believe it will be found that most of the conclusions arrived at in "ihis work have no necessary connexion with any particular views respecting the ulterior analysis. Logic is com- mon ground on which the partisans of Hartley and of Reid, of Locke and of Kant may meet and join hands. Particular and detached opinions of all these thinkers will no doubt occa- sionally be controverted, since all of them were logicians as well as meta- physicians ; but the field on which their principal battles have been fought, lies beyond the boundaries of our science. It cannot, indeed, be pretended that logical principles can be alto- gether irrelevant to those more ab- struse discussions ; nor is it possible but that the view we are led to take of the problem which logic proposes, must have a tendency favourable to the adoption of some one opinion, on these controverted subjects, rather than another. For metaphysics, in endeavouring to solve its own peculiar problem, must employ means, the validity of which falls under the cognizamce of logic. It proceeds, no doubt, as far as possible, merely by a closer and more attentive interroga- tion of our consciousness, or more properly speaking, of our memory ; and so far is not amenable to logic. But wherever this method is insuffi- cient to attain the end of its inqiiiries, it must proceed, like other sciences, by means of evidence. Now, the moment this science begins to draw inferences from evidence, logic be- comes the sovereign judge whether its inferences are well grounded, or what other inferences would be so. This, however, constitutes no nearer or other relation between logic and metaphysics, than that which exists between logic and every other science. And I can conscientiously affirm, that no one proposition laid down in this work has been adopted for the sake of establishing, or with any reference to its fitness for being employed in establishing, preconceived opinions in any department of knowledge or of inquiry on which the speculative world is still undecided.* * The view taken in the text, of the defi- nition and purpose of Logic, stands ia marked opposition to that of the scliool of philosophy wliich, in this country, is re- presented by the writings of Sir William Hamilton and of his numerous pupils. Logic, as this school conceives it, is " the Science of the Formal Laws of Thought ;" a definition framed for the express purpose of excluding, as irrelevant to Logic, what- ever relates to Belief and Disbelief, or to the pursuit of truth as such, and restrict- ing the science to that very limited portion of its total province, which has reference to the conditions, not of Truth, but of Consistency. What I have thought it use- ful to say in opposition to this limitation of the field of Logic, has been said at some length in a separate worl<, first published in 1865, and entitled An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy, and of the Principal Philosophical Questions dis- cussed in his Writings. For the purposes of the present Treatise, I am content that the justification of the larger extension which I gave to the domain of the science, should rest on the sequel of the Treatise itself. Some remarks on the relation which the Logic of Consistency bears to the Logic of Truth, and on the place wliich that par- ticular part occupies in the whole to which it belongs, will be found in the present volume (J3ook II, chap. iii. § 9). BOOK I. OF NAMES AND PEOPOSITIONa •' La scolastique, qui produisit dans la logique, comme dans la morale, et dans une pai'tie de la metapliysiqiie, une subtilit6, une precision d'idees, dont I'habitude inconnue aux anciens, a contribue plus qu'on ne croit au progres de la bonne pliilosophie."— Co-NDORCET, Vie de Turgot. " To the scboolmen the vulgar languages are principally indebted for what precision and analytic subtlety they possess." — Sir W. Hamilton, Discussions in Philosophy/,' OP NAMES AND PEOPOSITIONg. CHAPTER I. 'OP THE NECESSITY OF COMMENCING WITH AN ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE. § I. It is so much the established practice of Avriters on logic to com- mence their treatises by a few general observations (in most cases, it is true, rather meagre) on Terms and their varieties, that it will, perhaps, scarcely be required from me in merely follow- ing the common usage, to be as parti- cular in assigning my reasons, as it is usually expected that those should be who deviate from it. The practice, indeed, is recom- mended by considerations far too obvious to require a formal justifica- tion. Logic is a portion of the Art of Thinking : Language is evidently, and by the admission of all philoso- phers, one of the principal instruments or helps of thought ; and any imper- fection in the instrument, or in the mode of employing it, is confessedly liable, still more than in almost any other art, to confuse and impede the process, and destroy all ground of confidence in the result. For a mind not previously versed in the meaning a,nd right use of the various kinds of words, to attempt the study of methods of philosophising, would be as if some one should attempt to become an astronomical observer, having never learned to adjust the focal distance of his optical instruments so as to see distinctly. Since Reasoning, or Inference, the J)rincipal subject of logic, is an opera- tion which usually takes place by means of words, and in complicated cases can take place in no other way ; those who have not a thorough insight into the signification and purposes of words, will be under chances, amount- ing almost to certainty, of reasoning or inferring incorrectly. And logi- cians have generally felt that unless, in the very first stage, they removed this source of error ; unless they taught their pupil to put away the glasses which distort the object, and to use those which are adapted to his purpose in such a manner as to assist, not per- plex, his vision ; he would not be in a condition to practise the remaining part of their discipline with any pro- spect of advantage. Therefore it is that an inquiry into language, so far as is needful to guard against the errors to which it gives rise, has at all times been deemed a necessary pre- liminary to the study of logic. But there is another reason, of a still more fundamental nature, why the import of words should be the earliest subject of the logician's con- sideration : because without it he can- not examine into the import of Pro- positions. Now this is a subject which stands on the very threshold of the science of logic. The object of logic, as defined in the Introductory Chapter, is to ascer- tain how we come by that portion of our knowledge (much the greatest portion) which is not intuitive : and by what criterion we can, in matters not self-evident, distinguish between t2 INAMES AND l>ROPOSlTlONg. things proved and things not proved, between what is worthy and what is unworthy of belief. Of the various questions which present themselves to our inquiring faculties, some re- ceive an answer from direct conscious- ness, others, if resolved at all, can only be resolved by means of evidence. Logic is concerned with these last. But before inquiring into the mode of resolving questions, it is necessary to inquire what are those which offer themselves ; what questions are con- ceivable ; what inquiries are there, to which mankind have either obtained, or been able to imagine it possible that they should obtain, an answer. This point is best ascertained by a survey and analysis of Propositions. § 2. The answer to every question which it is possible to frame, must be contained in a Proposition, or Asser- tion. Whatever can be an object of belief, or even of disbelief, must, when put into words, assume the form of a proposition. All truth and all error lie in propositions. What, by a con- venient misapplication of an abstract term, we call a Truth, means simply a True Proposition ; and errors are false propositions. To know the im- port of all possible propositions, would be to know all questions which can be raised, all matters which are sus- ceptible of being either believed or disbelieved. How many kinds of in- quiries can be propounded ; how many kinds of judgments can be made ; and how many kinds of propositions is it possible to frame with a meaning ; are but different forms of one and the same question. Since, then, the ob- jects of all Belief and of all Inquiry express themselves in propositions ; a sufficient scrutiny of Propositions and of their varieties will apprize us what questions mankind have actually asked of themselves, and what, in the nature of answers to those questions, they have actually thought they had grounds to believe. Now the first glance at a proposi- tion shows that it is formed by put- ting together two names. A proposi- tion, according to the common simple definition, which is sufficient for our purpose, is, discourse, in ichich some- thing is affirmed or denied of some- thing. Thus, in the proposition, Gold is yellow, the quality yelloiu is affirmed of the substance gold. In the pro- position, Franklin was not born in England, the fact expressed by the words horn in England is denied of the man Pranklin. Every proposition consists of three parts : the Subject, the Predicate, and the Copula. The predicate is the name denoting that which is affirmed or denied. The subject is the name denoting the person or thing which something is affirmed or denied of. The copula is the sign denoting that there is an affirmation or denial ; and thereby enabling the hearer or reader to distinguish a proposition from any other kind of discourse. Thus, in the proposition, the earth is round, the Predicate is the word round, which denotes the quality affirmed, or (as the phrase is) predicated : the earth, words denoting the object which that quality is affirmed of, compose the Subject ; the word is, which serves as the connecting mark between the subject and predicate, to show that one of them is affirmed of the other, is called the Copula. Dismissing, for the present, the copula, of which more will be said hereafter, every proposition, then, consists of at least two names ; brings together two names, in a particular manner. This is already a first step towards what we are in quest of. It appears from this, that for an act of belief, one object is not sufficient ; the simplest act of belief supposes, and has something to do with, two objects : two names, to say the least ; and (since the names must be names of something) two nameable things. A large class of thinkers would cut the matter short by saying, two ideas. They would say, that the subject and predicate are both of them names of ideas, the idea of gold, for instance, NECESSITY OF AN ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE. 13 and the idea of yellow ; and that what takes place (or part of what takes place) in the act of belief, con- sists in bringing (as it is often ex- pressed) one of these ideas under the other. Eut this we are not yet in a condition to say : whether such be the correct mode of describing the phenomenon, is an after considera- tion. The result with which for the present we must be contented, is, that in every act of belief tico objects are in some manner taken cognizance of ; that there can be no belief claimed, or question propounded, which does not embrace two distinct (either material or intellectual) sub- jects of thought ; each of them cap- able, or not, of being conceived by itself, but incapable of being believed bj'- itself. I may say, for instance, " the sun." The word has a meaning, and suggests that meaning to the mind of any one who is listening to me. But suppose I ask him. Whether it is true : whether he believes it ? He can give no answer. There is as yet nothing to believe, or to disbelieve. Now, however, let me make, of all possible assertions respecting the sun, the one which involves the least of reference to any object besides itself ; let me say, " the sun exists." Here, at once, is something which a person can say he believes. But here instead of only one, we find two distinct objects of conception : the sun is one object ; existence is another. Let it not be said that this second conception, existence, is involved in the first ; for the sun may be conceived as no longer existing. " 'J'he sun " does not convey all the meaning that is conveyed by " the sun exists : " " my father " does not include all the meaning of "my father exists," for he may be dead ; " a round square " does not include the meaning of '* a round souare exists," for it does not and cannot exist. When I say " the sun," " my father," or " a round square," I do not call upon the hearer for any belief or disbelief, nor can either the one or the other be afforded me ; but if I say, "the sun exists," " my father exists," or a " round square exists," I call for belief ; and should, in the first of the three in- stances, meet with it ; in the second, with belief or disbelief, as the case might be ; in the third, with dis- belief. § 3, This first step in the analysis of the object of belief, which, though so obvious, will be found to be not unimportant, is the only one which we shall find it practicable to make without a preliminary survey of lan- guage. If we attempt to proceed further in the same path, that is, to analyse any further the import of Propositions, we find forced upon us, as a subject of previous consideration, the import of Names. For every pro- position consists of two names ; and every proposition affirms or denies one of these names, of the other. Now what we do, what passes in our mind, when we affirm or deny two names of one another, must depend on what they are names of ; since it is with reference to that, and not to the mere names themselves, that we make the affirmation or denial. Here, therefore, we find a new reason why the signification of names, and the relation generally between names and the things signified by them, must occupy the preliminary stage of the inquiry we are engaged in. It may be objected that the mean- ing of names can guide us at most only to the opinions, possibly the foolish and groundless opinions, which mankind have formed concerning things, and that as the object of philosophy is truth, not opinion, the philosopher should dismiss words and look into things themselves, to ascer- tain what questions can be asked and answered in regard to them. This advice (which no one has it in his power to follow) is in reality an ex- hortation to discard the whole fruits of the labours of his predecessors, and conduct himself as if he were the 14 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. first person who had ever turned an inquiring eye upon nature. What does any one's personal knowledge of Things amount to, after subtracting all which he has acquired by means of the words of other people ? Even after he has learned as much as people usually do learn from others, will the notions of things contained in his individual mind afford as sufficient a basis for a catalogue raisonne as the notions which are in the minds of all mankind ? In any enumeration and classifica- tion of Things, which does not set out from their names, no varieties of things will of course be comprehended but those recognised by the particular inquirer ; and it will still remain to be established, by a subsequent exami- nation of names, that the enumeration has omitted nothing which ought to have been included. But if we begin with names, and use them as our clue to the things, we bring at once before us all the distinctions which have been recognised, not by a single inquirer, but by all inquirers taken together. It doubtless may, and I believe it will, be found, that man- kind have multiplied the varieties unnecessarily, and have imagined dis- tinctions among things, where there were only distinctions in the manner of naming them. But we are not entitled to assume this in the com- mencement. We must begin by re- cognising the distinctions made by ordinary language. If some of these appear, on a close examination, not to be fundamental, the enumeration of the different kinds of realities may be abridged accordingly. But to impose upon the facts in the first instance the yoke of a theory, while the grounds of the theory are reserved for discussion in a subsequent stage, is not a course which a logician can reasonably adopt. CHAPTER II. OF NAMES. § I. "A NAME," says Hobbes,* ** is a word taken at pleasure to serve for a mark which may raise in our mind a thought like to some thought we had before, and which being pro- nounced to others, may be to them a sign of what thought the speaker had f before in his mind." This simple definition of a name, as a word (or set of words) serving the double purpose of a mark to recall to our- selves the likeness of a former thought, and a sign to make it known to others, appears unexceptionable. Names, indeed, do much more than this ; but whatever else they do, grows out of, and is the result of this : as will appear in its proper place. Are names more properly said to be the names of things, or of our ideas of things ? The first is the ex- pression in common use ; the last is that of some metaphysicians, who con- ceived that in adopting it they were introducing a highly important dis- tinction. The eminent thinker, just quoted, seems to countenance the latter opinion. " But seeing," he con- tinues, " names ordered in speech (as is defined) are signs of our concep- tions, it is manifest they are not signs of the things themselves ; for that the sound of this word stone should be the sign of a stone, cannot be understood in any sense but this, that he that hears it collects that he that pronounces it thinks of a stone." If it be merely meant that the con- ception alone, and not the thing itself,. is recalled by the name, or imparted to the hearer, this of course cannot, be denied. Nevertheless, there seems, good reason for adhering to the. common usage, and calling (as indeed Hobbes himself does in other places), the word sun the name of the sun^ * Computation or Logic, chap. ii. t In the original "had, or had not."- These last words, as involving a subtlety- foreign to onr present purpose, I have for-, borne to quote... NAMES. 15 and not the name of our idea of the sun. For names are not intended only to make the hearer conceive what we conceive, but also to inform him what we believe. Now, when I use a name for the purpose of express- ing a belief, it is a belief concerning the thing itself, not concerning my idea of it. When I say, "the sun is the cause of day," I do not mean that my idea of the sun causes or excites in me the idea of day : or in other words, that thinking of the sun makes me think of day. I mean, that a certain physical fact, which is called the sun's presence (and which, in the ultimate analysis, resolves itself into sensations, not ideas) causes another physical fact, which is called day. It seems proper to consider a word as the name of that which we intend to be understood by it when we use it ; of that which any fact that we assert of it is to be understood of ; that, in short, concerning which, when we employ the word, we intend to give information. Names, therefore, shall always be spoken of in this work as the names of things themselves, and not merely of our ideas of things. But the question now arises, of what things ? and to answer this it is neces- sary to take into consideration the different kinds of names. § 2. It is usual, before examining the various classes into which names are commonly divided, to begin by distinguishing from names of every description, those words which are not names, but only parts of names. Among such are reckoned particles, as of, to, trull/, often; the inflected cases of nouns substantive, as me, him, Johns ; and even adjectives, as large, heavy. These words do not express things of which anything can be afiii'med or denied. We cannot say. Heavy fell, or A heavy fell ; Truly, or A truly, was asserted ; Of, or An of, was in the room. Unless, indeed, we are speaking of the mere words themselves, as when we say, Truly is an English word, or, Heavy is an adjective. In that case they are com- plete names, viz. names of those parti- cular sounds, or of those particular collections of written characters. This employment of a word to denote the mere letters and syllables of which it is composed, was termed by the school- men the suppositio materialis of the word. In any other sense we cannot introduce one of these words into the subject of a proposition, unless in combination with other words ; as, A heavy body fell, A truly important fact was asserted, A member of parlia- ment was in the room. An adjective, however, is capable of standing by itself as the predicate of a proposition ; as when we say. Snow is white j and occasionally even as the subject, for we may say. White is an agreeable colour. The adjective is often said to be so used by a gram- matical ellipsis : Snow is white, in- stead of Snow is a white object : White is an agreeable colour, instead of, A white colour, or, The colour white, is agreeable. The Greeks and Romans were allowed, by the rules of their language, to employ this ellipsis universally in the subject as well as in the predicate of a proposition. In English this cannot, generally speak- ing, be done. We may say, The earth is round ; but we cannot say, Round is easily moved ; we must say, A round object. This distinction, however, is rather grammatical than logical. Since there is no difference of meaning between round, and a round object, it is only custom which prescribes that on any given occasion one shall be used, and not the other. We shall, therefore, without scruple, speak of adjectives as names, whether in their own right, or as representa- tive of the more circuitous forms of expression above exemplified. The other classes of subsidiary words have no title whatever to be considered as names. An adverb, or an accusative case, cannot under any circumstances (except when their mere letters and syllables are spoken of) figure as one of the terms of a proposition, i6 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. Words which are not capable of bemg used as names, but only as parts of names, were called by some of the schoolmen Syncategorematio terms : from citv, with, and KaTrjyop^oj, to predicate, because it was only with some other word that they could be predicated. A word which could be used either as the subject or predicate of a proposition without being accom- panied by any other word, was termed by the same authorities a Categore- matic term. A combination of one or more Categorematic, and one or more Syncategorematiq words, as A heavy body, or A court of justice, they sometimes called a mixed term ; but this seems a needless multiplica- tion of technical expressions. A mixed term is, in the only useful sense of the word, Categorematic. It belongs to the class of what have been called many- worded names. Tor, as one word is frequently not a name, but only part of a name, so a number of words often compose one single name, and no more. These words, " The place which the wisdom or policy of antiquity had destined for the residence of the Abyssinian princes," form in the estimation of the logician only one name ; one Categorematic term. A mode of de- termining whether any set of words makes only one name, or more than one, is by predicating something of it, and observing whether, by this pre- dication, we make only one assertion or several. Thus, when we say, John Nokes, who was the mayor of the town, died yesterday — by this predi- cation we make but one assertion ; whence it appears that " John Nokes, who was the mayor of the town," is no more than one name. It is true that in this proposition, besides the asser- tion that John Nokes died yesterday, there is included another insertion, namely, that John Nokes was mayor of the town. But this last assertion was already made : we did not make it by adding the predicate, "died yesterday." Suppose, however, that thQ words had been, John Nokes and the mayor of the town, they would have formed two names instead of one. For when we say, John Nokes and the mayor of the town died yes- terday, we make two assertions : one, that John Nokes died yesterday ; the other, that the mayor of the town died yesterday. It being needless to illustrate at any greater length the subject of many-worded names, we proceed to the distinctions which have been established among names, not accord- ing to the words they are composed of, but according to their significa- tion. § 3. All names are names of some- thing, real or imaginary ; but all things have not names appropriated to them individually. Tor some in- dividual objects we require, and con- sequently have, separate distinguish- ing names ; there is a name for every person, and for every remarkable place. Other objects, of which we have not occasion to speak so fre- quently, we do not designate by a name of their own ; but when the necessity arises for naming them, we do so by putting together several words, each of which, by itself, might be and is used for an indefinite num- ber of other objects ; as when I say, this stone : " this " and " stone " being, each of them, names that may be used of many other objects besides the par- ticular one meant, though the only object of which they can both be used at the given moment, consistently with their signification, may be the one of which I wish to speak. Were this the sole purpose for which names, that are common to more things than one, could be em- ployed ; if they only served, by mutually limiting each other, to afford a designation for such individual ob- jects as have no names of their own ; they could only be ranked among contrivances for economizing the use of language. But it is evident that this is not their sole function. It is by their means that we are enabled NAMES. 17 to assert general propositions ; to affirm or deny any predicate of an indefinite number of things at once. The distinction, therefore, between general names, and individual or singu- lar names, is fundamental ; and may be considered as the first grand divi- y sion of names. ^ A general name is familiarly de- fined, a name which is capable of being truly affirmed, in the same sense, of each of an indefinite number of things. An individual or singular name is a name which is only capable of being truly affirmed, in the same sense, of one thing. Thus, man is capable of being truly affirmed of John, George, Mary, and other persons without assignable limit ; and it is affirmed of all of them in the same sense ; for the word man expresses certain qualities, and when we predicate it of those persons, we assert that they all possess those qualities. But John is only capable of being truly affirmed of one single person, at least in the same sense. Tor, though there are many persons who bear that name, it is not con- ferred upon them to indicate any qualities, or anything which belongs to them in common ; and cannot be said to be aifirmed of them in any sense at all, consequently not in the same sense. "The king who suc- ceeded William the Conqueror," is also an individual name. For, that there cannot be more than one person of whom it can be truly aflSrmed, is implied in the meaning of the words. Even " not seem to have been intended as a classification of Nameable Things, in the sense of ' an enumeration of all kinds of Things which are capable of being made predicates, or of haviiiganythiug predicated of them.' I hey seem to iiave been rather intended as a generalization of predicates; an analysis of the final import of predica- tion. Viewed in tins light, they are not open to tht^ objections offered by Mr. Mill. The proper question to ask is not — In what Category are we to place sensations or other feelings or states of mind? but. Under what Categories can we predicate regard- ing states of mind? Take, for example, Hope. When we say tiiat it is a state of mind, we predicate Substance : we may also describe liow great it is (Quantity), what is tiie quality of it, pleasurable or painful (Quality), what it has reference to (Relation). Aristotle seems to hare framed § 2. Before recommencing, under better auspices, the attempt made with such imperfect success by the early logicians, we must take notice of an unfortunate ambiguity in all the concrete names which correspond to the most general of all abstract terms, the word Existence. When we have occasion for a name which shall be capable of denoting whatever exists, as contradistinguished from non- entity or Nothing, there is hardly a word applicable to the purpose which is not also, and even more familiarly, taken in a sense in which it denotes only substances. But substances are not all that exists ; attributes, if such things are to be spoken of, must be said to exist ; feelings certainly exist. Yet when we speak of an object, or of a thing, we are almost always supposed to mean a substance. There seems a kind of contradiction in using such an expression as that one thing is merely an attribute of another thing. And the announce- ment of a Classification of Things would, I believe, prepare most readers the Categories on the plan— Here is an in- dividual ; wtiat is the final analysis of all tliat we can predicate about him? " This is doubtless a true statement of the leading idea in the classification. The Category Ovaia was certainly understood by Aristotle to be a general name for all possible answers to the questions Quid sit ? w lien asked rei^pecting a concrete indi- vidual ; as the other Categories are names comprehending all possilile answers to the questions Quantum sit? Quale sit? &c. In Aristotle's conception, tiierefore, the Cate- gories may not have been a classification of Thintrs ; but they were soon converted into one by his scholastic followers, who cer- tainly regarded and treated them as a classification of Things, and carried them out as such, dividing down the Category Substance us a naturalist mignt do, into the different classes of physical or meta- physical objects as distinguished from attributes, and the other Categories into the principal varieties of quantity, quality, relation, &c. It is, therefore, a just sub- ject of complaint against them, that they had no Category of Feeling. Feeling is assu'cdly predicable as. a summum genus, of every particular kind of feeling, for in- stance, as in Mr. Bain's example, of Hope : but it cannot be brought within any of the Categories as interpreted either by Aristotle or by his followers. THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 31 for an enumeration like those in natural history, beginning with the great divisions of animal, vegetable, and mineral, and subdividing them into classes and orders. If, rejecting the word Thing, we endeavour to find another of a more general import, or at least more exclusively confined to that general import, a word denoting all that exists, and connoting only simple existence ; no word might be presumed fitter for such a purpose than being : originally the present participle of a verb which in one of its meanings is exactly equivalent to the verb exists; and therefore suitable, even by its grammatical formation, to be the concrete of the abstract exist- ence. But this word, strange as the fact may appear, is still more com- pletely spoiled for the purpose which it seemed expressly made for, than the word Thing. Being is, by custom, exactly synonymous with substance ; except that it is free from a slight taint of a second ambiguity ; being applied impartially to matter and to mind, while substance, though ori- ginally and in strictness applicable to both, is apt to suggest in preference the idea of matter. Attributes are never called Beings ; nor are feelings. A being is that which excites feelings, and which possesses attributes. The soul is called a Being ; God and angels are called Beings ; but if we were to say, extension, colour, wis- dom, virtue, are beings, we should perhaps be suspected of thinking with some of the ancients, that the cardinal virtues are animals ; or, at the least. of holding with the Platonic school the doctrine of self-existent Ideas, or with the followers of Epicurus that of Sensible Forms, which detach them- selves in every direction from bodies, and by coming in contact with our organs, cause our perceptions. We should be supposed, in short, to be- lieve that Attributes are Substances. In consequence of this perversion of the word Being, philosophers looking about for something to supply its place, laid their hands upon the word Entity, a piece of barbarous Latin, invented by the schoolmen to be used as an abstract name, in which class its grammatical form would seem to place it ; but being seized by logicians in distress to stop a leak in their terminology, it has ever since been used as a concrete name. The kindred word essence, bom at the same time and of the same parents, scarcely underwent a more complete transformation when, from being the abstract of the verb to he, it came to denote something sufficiently concrete to be enclosed in a glass bottle. The word Entity, since it settled down into a concrete name, has retained its universality of signification somewhat less im- paired than any of the names before mentioned. Yet the same gradual decay to which, after a certain age, all the language of psychology seems liable, has been at work even here. If you call virtue an entity, you are indeed somewhat less strongly sus- pected of believing it to be a sub- stance than if you called it a being ; but you are by no means free from the suspicion. Every word which was originally intended to connote mere existence, seems, after a time, to enlarge its connotation to separate existence, or existence freed from the condition of belonging to a substance ; which condition being precisely what constitutes an attribute, attributes are gradually shut out; and along with them feelings, which in ninety - nine cases out of a hundred have no other name than that of the attribute which is grounded on them. Strange that when the greatest embarrassment felt by all who have any considerable number of thoughts to express, is to find a sufficient variety of precise words fitted to express them, there should be no practice to which even scientific thinkers are more addicted than that of taking valuable words to express ideas which are sufficiently expressed by other words already appropriated to them. When it is impossible to obtain good 32 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. tools, the next best thing is to under- stand thoroughly the defects of those we have. I have therefore warned the reader of the ambiguity of the names which, for want of better, I am necessitated to employ. It must now be the writer's endeavour so to employ them as in no case to leave the mean- ing doubtful or obscure. No one of the above terms being altogether un- ambiguous, I shall not confine myself to any one, but shall employ on each occasion the word which seems least likely in the particular case to lead to misunderstanding ; nor do I pretend to use either these or any other words with a rigorous adherence to one single sense. To do so would often leave us without a word to express what is signified by a known word in some one or other of its senses : unless authors had an unlimited licence to coin new words, together with (what it would be more difficult to assume) unlimited power of making readers understand them. Nor would it be wise in a writer, on a subject involving so much of abstraction, to deny himself the advantage derived from even an im- proper use of a term, when, by means of it, some familiar association is called up which brings the meaning home to the mind, as it were by a flash. The difficulty both to the writer and reader, of the attempt which must be made to use vague words so as to convey a precise meaning, is not wholly a matter of regret. It is not unfitting that logical treatises should afford an example of that, to facilitate which is among the most important uses of logic. Philosophical language will for a long time, and popular language still longer, retain so much of vagueness and ambiguity, that logic would be of little value if it did not, among its other advantages, exercise the understanding in doing its work neatly and correctly with these imperfect tools. After this preamble it is time to proceed to our enumeration. We shall commence with Feelings, the simplest class of nameable things ; the term Feeling being of course under- stood in its most enlarged sense. I. Feelings, or States of Con- sciousness. § 3. A Feeling and a State of Con- sciousness are, in the language of philosophy, equivalent expressions : everything is a feeling of which the mind is conscious ; everything which it feels, or, in other words, which forms a part of its own sentient exist- ence. In popular language Feeling is not always synonymous with State of Consciousness ; being often taken more peculiarly for those states which are conceived as belonging to the sensitive, or to the emotional, phasis of our nature, and sometimes, with a still narrower restriction, to the emo- tional alone, as distinguished from what are conceived as belonging to the percipient or to the intellectual phasis. But this is an admitted departure from correctness of lan- guage ; just as, by a popular perver- sion the exact converse of this, the word Mind is withdrawn from its rightful generality of signification, and restricted to the intellect. The still greater perversion by which Feeling is sometimes confined not only to bodily sensations, but to the sensations of a single sense, that of touch, needs not to be more particu- larly adverted to. Feeling, in the proper sense of the term, is a genus, of which Sensation, Emotion, and Thought, are subordi- nate species. Un der the word Thought is here to be included whatever we are internally conscious of when we are said to think ; from the conscious- ness we have when we think of a red colour without having it before our eyes, to the most recondite thoughts of a philosopher or poet. Be it re- membered, however, that by a thought is to be understood what passes in the mind itself, and not any object external to the mind, which the person is commonly said to be thinking of. He may be thinking of the sun, or of THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 33 God, but the sun and God are not thoughts ; his mental image, however, of the sun, and his idea of God, are thoughts ; states of his mind, not of the objects themselves ; and so also is his belief of the existence of the sun, or of God ; or his disbelief, if the case be so. Even imaginary objects (which are said to exist only in our ideas) are to be distinguished from our ideas of them. I may think of a hobgoblin, as I may think of the loaf which was eaten yesterday, or of the flower which will bloom to-morrow. But the hobgoblin which never existed is not the same thing with my idea of a hobgoblin, any more than the loaf which once existed is the same thing with my idea of a loaf, or the flower which does not yet exist, but which will exist, is the same with my idea of a flower. They are all, not thoughts, but objects of thought ; though at the present time all the objects are alike non-existent. In like manner, a Sensation is to be carefully distinguished from the object which causes the sensation ; our sensation of white from a white object: nor is it less to be distinguished from the attribute whiteness, which we ascribe to the object in consequence of its exciting the sensation. Unfor- tunately for clearness and due dis- crimination in considering these sub- jects, our sensations seldom receive separate names. "We have a name for the objects which produce in us a certain sensation : the word white. We have a name for the quality in those objects, to which we ascribe the sensation : the name whiteness. But when we speak of the sensation itself (as we have not occasion to do this often except in our scientific speculations), language, which adapts itself for the most part only to the common uses of life, has provided us with no single-worded or immediate designation ; we must employ a cir- cumlocution, and say, The sensation of white, or The sensation of white- ness ; we must denominate the sensa- tion either from the object, or from the attribute, by which it is excited. Yet the sensation, though it never does, might very well be conceived to exist, without anything whatever to excite it. We can conceive it as arising spontaneously in the mind. But if it so arose, we should have no name to denote it which would not be a misnomer. In the case of our sensations of hearing we are better provided ; we have the word Sound, and a whole vocabulary of words to denote the various kinds of sounds. For as we are often conscious of these sensations in the absence of any perceptible object, we can more easily conceive having them in the absence of any object whatever. We need only shut our eyes and listen to music, to have a conception of an uni- verse with nothing in it except sounds, and ourselves hearing them : and what is easily conceived separately, easily obtains a separate name. But in gene- ral our names of sensations denote in- discriminately the sensation and the attribute. Thus, colour stands for the sensations of white, red, &c., but also for the quality in the coloured object. We talk of the colours of things as among their properties. § 4. In the case of sensations, another distinction has also to be kept in view, which is often con- founded, and never without mis- chievous consequences. This is, the distinction between the sensation it- self, and the state of the bodily organs which precedes the sensation, and which constitutes the physical agency by which it is produced. One of the sources of confusion on this subject is the division commonly made of feel- ings into Bodily and Mental. Philoso- phically speaking, there is no founda- tion at all for this distinction ; even sensations are states of the sentient mind, not states of the body, as dis- tinguished from it. What I am con- scious of when I see the colour blue, is B^ feeling of blue colour, which is one thing ; the picture on my retina, or the phenomenon of hitherto mys- 34 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. terious nature which takes place in my optic nerve or in my brain, is another thing, of which I am not at all conscious, and which scientific in- vestigation alone could have apprised me of. These are states of my body : but the sensation of blue, which is the consequence of these states of body, is not a state of body : that which perceives and is conscious is called Mind. When sensations are called bodily feelings, it is only as being the class of feelings which are immediately occasioned by bodily btates ; whereas the other kinds of feelings, thoughts, for instance, or emotions, are immediately excited not by anything acting upon the bodily organs, but by sensations, or by previous thoughts. This, however, is a distinction not in our feelings, but in the agency which produces our feelings : all of them when actually produced are states of mind. Besides the affection of our bodily organs from without, and the sensa- tion thereby produced in our minds, many writers admit a third link in the chain of phenomena, which they call a Perception, and which consists in the recognition of an external object as the exciting cause of the sensation. This perception, they say, is an act of the mind, proceeding from its own spontaneous activity ; while in a sensation the mind is pas- sive, being merely acted upon by the outward object. And according to some metaphysicians, it is by an act of the mind, similar to perception, except in not being preceded by any sensation, that the existence of God, the soul, and other hyperphysical objects is recognised. These acts of what is termed per- ception, whatever be the conclusion xiltimately come to respecting their nature, must, I conceive, take their place among the varieties of feelings or states of mind. In so classing them, I have not the smallest inten- tion of declaring or insinuating any theory as to the law of mind in which these mental processes may be sup- posed to originate, or the conditions under which they may be legitimate or the reverse. Far less do I mean (as Dr. Whewell seems to suppose must be meant in an analogous case*) to indicate that as they are " merely states of mind," it is superfluous to inquire into their distinguishing pecu- liarities. I abstain from the inquiry as irrelevant to the science of logic. In these so-called perceptions, or direct recognitions by the mind, of objects, whether physical or spiritual, which are external to itself, I can see only cases of belief ; but of belief which claims to be intuitive, or inde- pendent of external evidence. "When a stone lies before me, I am conscious of certain sensations which I receive from it ; but if I say that these sen- sations come to me from an external object which I perceive, the meaning of these words is, that receiving the sensations, I intuitively believe that an external cause of those sensations exists. The laws of intuitive belief, and the conditions under which it is legitimate, are a subject which, as we have already so often remarked, be- longs not t'> logic, but to the science of the ultimate laws of the human mind. To the same region of speculation belongs all that can be said respecting the distinction which the German metaphysicians and their French and English followers so elaborately draw between the acts of the mind and its merely passive states; between what it receives from, and what it gives to, the crude materials of its experience. I am aware that with reference to the view which those writers take of the primary elements of thought and knowledge, this distinction is funda- mental. But for the present purpose, which is to examine, not the original groundwork of our knowledge, but how we come by that portion of it which is not original ; the difference between active and passive states of mind is of secondary importance. For us, they all are states of mindj * Philosophy 0/ the Jndwtive Sciences, voL i. p. 40. THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 35 they all are feelings ; by which, let it be said once more, I mean to imply nothing of passivity, but simply that they are psychological facts, facts which take place in the mind, and are to be carefully distinguished from the external or physical facts with which they may be connected either as effects or as causes. § 5. Among active states of mind, there is, however, one species which merits particular attention, because it forms a principal part of the con- notation of some important classes of names. I mean volitions, or acts of the will. When we speak of sentient beings by relative names, a large portion of the connotation of the name usually consists of the actions of those beings ; actions past, present, and possible or probable future. Take, for instance, the words Sovereign and Subject. What meaning do these words convey, but that of innumerable actions, done or to be done by the sovereign and the subjects, to or in regard to one another reciprocally ? So with the words physician and patient, leader and follower, tutor and pupil. In many cases the words also connote actions which would be done under certain contingencies by persons other than those denoted : as the words mortgagor and mortgagee, ob- ligor and obligee, and many other words expressive of legal relation, which connote what a court of justice would do to enforce the legal obligation if not fulfilled. There are also words which connote actions previously done by persons other than those denoted either by the name itself or by its correlative ; as the word brother. From those instances, it may be seen how large a portion of the connota- tion of names consists of actions. Now what is an action ? Not one thing, but a series of two things ; the state of mind called a volition, fol- lowed by an effect. The volition or intention to produce the effect, is one thing ; the effect produced in conse- quepce of the iptei^tion, is another thing ; the two together constitute the action. I f onn the purpose of instantly moving nay arm ; that is a state of my mind : my arm (not being tied or paralytic) moves in obedience to my purpose ; that is a physical fact, con- sequent on a state of mind. The inten- tion, followed by the fact, or (if we prefer the expression) the fact when preceded and caused by the intention, is called the action of moving my arm. § 6. Of the first leading division of nameable things, viz., Feelings or States of Consciousness, we began by recognising three sub-divisions ; Sen- sations, Thoughts, and Emotions. The first two of these we have illus- trated at considerable length ; the third. Emotions, not being perplexed by similar ambiguities, does not re- quire similar exemplification. And, finally, we have found it necessary to add to these three a fourth species, commonly known by the name Voli- tions. We shall now proceed to the two remaining classes of nameable things ; all things which are regarded as external to the mind being con- sidered as belonging either to the class of Substances or to that of Attributes. II. Substances. Logicians have endeavoured to de- fine Substance and Attribute ; but their definitions are not so much attempts to draw a distinction between the things themselves, as instructions what difference it is customary to make in the grammatical structure of the sentence, according as we are speaking of substances or of attributes. Such definitions are rather lessons of English, or of Greek, Latin, or Ger- man, than of mental philosophy. An attribute, say the school logicians, must be the attribute of something : colour, for example, nmst be the colour of something ; goodness must be the goodness of something ; and if this something should cease to exist, or should cease to be connected with the ftttribiite, the existence of th^ J^Hri- 36 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. bute would be at an end, A substance, on the contrary, is self-existent ; in speaking about it, we need not put of after its name. A stone is not the stone of anything ; the moon is not the moon of anything, but simply the moon. Unless, indeed, the name which we choose to give to the sub- stance be a relative name ; if so, it must be followed either by of, or by some other particle, implying, as that proposition does, a reference to some- thing else : but then the other char- acteristic peculiarity of an attribute would fail ; the something might be destroyed, and the substance might still subsist. Thus, a father must be the father of something, and so far resembles an attribute, in being re- ferred to something besides himself : if there were no child, there would be no father : but this, when we look into the matter, only means that we should not call him father. The man called father might still exist though there were no child, as he existed be- fore there was a child : and there would be no contradiction in suppos- ing him to exist, though the whole uni- verse except himself were destroyed. But destroy all white substances, and where would be the attribute white- ness ? Whiteness, without any white thing, is a contradiction in terms. This is the nearest approach to a solution of the difficulty, that will be found in the common treatises on logic. It will scarcely be thought to be a satisfactory one. If an attribute is distinguished from a substance by being the attribute of something, it seems highly necessary to understand what is meant by of ; a particle which needs explanation too much itself, to be placed in front of the explanation of anything else. And as for the self -existence of substance, it is very true that a substance may be con- ceived to exist without any other sub- stance, but so also may an attribute without any other attribute ; and we can no more imagine a substance with- out attributes than we can imagine attributes withput a sub^taijce. Metaphysicians, however, have probed the question deeper, and given an account of Substance considerably more satisfactory than this. Substances are usually distinguished as Bodies or Minds. Of each of these, philosophers have at length provided us with a defi- nition which seems unexceptionable. § 7. A body, according to the re- ceived doctrine of modem metaphysi- cians, may be defined, the external cause to which we ascribe our sensa- tions. When I see and touch a piece of gold, I am conscious of a sensation of yellow colour, and sensations of hard- ness and weight ; and by varying the mode of handling, I may add to these sensations many others completely distinct from them. The sensations are all of which I am directly con- scious ; but I consider them as pro- duced by something not only existing independently of my will, but externa] to my bodily organs and to my mind. This external something I call a body. It may be asked, how come we to ascribe our sensations to any external cause ? And is there sufficient ground for so ascribing them ? It is known, that there are metaphysicians who have raised a controversy on the point ; maintaining that we are not warranted in referring our sensations to a cause such as we understand by the word Body, or to any external cause whatever. Though we have no concern here with this controversy, nor with the metaphysical niceties on which it turns, one of the best ways of showing what is meant by Sub- stance is, to consider what position it is necessary to take up, in order to main- tain its existence against opponents. It is certain, then, that a part of our notion of a body consists of the notion of a number of sensations of our own, or of other sentient beings, habitually occurring simultaneously. My conception of the table at which I am writing is compounded of its visible form and size, which are com- plex sensations of sight ; its tangible form and size, which a,XQ comple^f THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 37 sensations of our organs of touch and of our muscles ; its weight, which is also a sensation of touch and of the muscles ; its colour, which is a sensa- tion of sight ; its hardness, which is a sensation of the muscles ; its com- position, which is another word for all the varieties of sensation which we receive under various circumstances from the wood of which it is made, and so forth. All or most of these various sensations frequently are, and, as we learn by experience, always might be, experienced simultaneously, or in many different orders of succes- sion at our own choice : and hence the thought of any one of them makes us think of the others, and the whole becomes mentally amalgamated into one mixed state of consciousness, which, in the language of the school of Locke and Hartley, is termed a Complex Idea. Now, there are philosophers who have argued as follows. If we con- ceive an orange to be divested of its natural colour without acquiring any new one ; to lose its softness without becoming hard, its roundness without becoming square or pentagonal, or of any other regular or irregular figure whatever ; to be deprived of size, of weight, of taste, of smell ; to lose all its mechanical and all its chemical properties, and acquire no new ones ; to become in short, invisible, intan- gible, imperceptible not only by all our senses, but by the senses of all other sentient beings, real or possible ; no- thing, say these thinkers, would re- main. For of what nature, they ask, could be the residuum ? and by what token could it manifest its presence ? To the unreflecting its existence seems to rest on the evidence of the senses. But to the senses nothing is appa- rent except the sensations. We know, indeed, that these sensations are bound together by some law ; they do not come together at random, but accord- ing to a systematic order, which is part of the order established in the universe. When we experience one of these sensations, we usually experi- ence the others also, or know that we have it in our power to experience them. But a fixed law of connection, making the sensations occur together, does not, say these philosophers, necessarily require what is called a substratum to support them. The conception of a substratum is but one of many possible forms in which that connection presents itself to our imagi- nation ; a mode of, as it were, re- alizing the idea. If there be such a substratum, suppose it at this instant miraculously annihilated, and let the sensations continue to occur in the same order, and how would the sub- stratum be missed ? By what signs j should we be able to discover that its existence had terminated ? Should we not have as much reason to believe : that it still existed as we now have ? And if we should not then be war- ranted in believing it, how can we be so now ? A body, therefore, according, to these metaphysicians, is not any- thing intrinsically different from the sensations which the body is said to produce in us ; it is, in short, a set of sensations, or rather, of possibilities of sensation, joined together according to a fixed law. j The controversies to which these speculations have given rise, and the doctrines which have been developed in the attempt to find a conclusive I answer to them, have been fruitful of important consequences to the Science j of Mind. The sensations (it was an- swered) which we are conscious of, and which we receive, not at random, but joined togetherin a certain uniform manner, imply not only a law or laws , of connection, but a cause external to our mind, which cause, by its own I laws, determines the laws according j to which the sensations are connected I and experienced. The schoolmen used to call this external cause by the name we have already employed, a *m6- stratuni ; and its attributes (as they expressed themselves) inherent, liter- ally stuck, in it. To this substratum the name Matter is usually given in philosophical discussions. It was 38 NAMES AKD PROPOSITIONS. soon, however, acknowledged by all who reflected on the subject, that the existence of matter cannot be proved by extrinsic evidence. The answer, therefore, now usually made to Berke- ley and his followers, is, that the belief is intuitive ; that mankind, in all ages, have felt themselves compelled, by a necessity of their nature, to refer their sensations to an external cause : that even those who deny it in theory, yield to the necessity in practice, and both in speech, thought, and feeling, do, equally with the vulgar, acknow- ledge their sensations to be the effects of something external to them : this knowledge, therefore, it is affirmed, is as evidently intuitive as our know- ledge of our sensations themselves is intuitive. And here the question merges in the fundamental problem of metaphysics properly so called : to which science we leave it. But although the extreme doctrine of the Idealist metaphysicians, that objects are nothing but our sensations and the laws which connect them, has not been generally adopted by subse- quent thinkers ; the point of most real importance is one on which those metaphysicians are now very generally considered to have made out their case : viz., that all we knoiooi objects, is the sensations which they give us, and the order of the occurrence of those sensations. Kant himself, on this point, is as explicit as Berkeley or Locke. However firmly convinced that there exists an universeof "Things in themselves," totally distinct from the universe of phenomena, or of things as they appear to our senses ; and even when bringing into use a tech- nical expression [Noumenon) to denote what the thing is in itself, as con- trasted with the representation of it in our minds ; he allows that this repre- sentation (the matter of which, he says, consists of our sensations, though the form is given by the laws of the mind itself) is all we know of the object : and that the real nature of the Thing is, and by the constitution of our faculties ever must remain, at least in the present state of existence, an impenetrable mystery to us. " Of things absolutely or in themselves," says Sir William Hamilton,* " be they external, be they internal, we know nothing, or know them only as incog- nisable ; and become aware of their incomprehensible existence, only as this is indirectly and accidentally revealed to us, through certain quali- ties related to our faculties of know- ledge, and which qualities, again, we cannot think as unconditioned, irre- lative, existent in and of themselves. All that we know is therefore phaeno- menal, — phsenomenal of the un- known." t The same doctrine is laid down in the clearest and strongest terms by M. Cousin, whose observa- tions on the subject are the more worthy of attention, as, in consequence of the ultra-German and ontological character of his philosophy in other respects, they may be regarded as the admissions of an opponent.^ * Discussions on Philosophy, &c. Appen- dix I. pp. 643-4. t It is to be regretted that Sir William Hamilton, though he often strenuously in- sists ou this doctrine, and though, in the passage quoted, he states it with a compre- hensiveness and force which leave nothing to be desired, did not consistently adhere to his own doctrine, but maintained along with it opinions with which it is utterly irreconcilable. See the third and other chapters of ^n Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy. t "Nous savons qu'il existe quelque chose hors de nous, parceque nous ne pou- vons expliquer nos perceptions sans lea rattacber k des causes distinctes de nous- mfimes ; n, et dans quel sens il est vrai de dire qu'elles sont." — Cours d'Hittoire de la Fhilosophie Morale au iSme siecle, 8me leqon. * An attempt, indeed, has been made by Reid and others, to establish that although some of the properties we ascribe to objects exist only in our sensations, others exist in the things themselves, being such as cannot possibly be copies of any impression upon the senses ; and they ask, from what sensations our notions of extension and figure have been derived? The gauntlet thrown down by Reid was taken up by Brown, who, applying greater powers of analysis than had previously been applied to tiie notions of extension and figure, pointed out that the sensations from which those notions are derived, are -ensations of touch, combined with sensations of a class previously too little adverted to by metaphysicians, those which have their seat in our muscular frame. His analysis, we authorized to deduce from the effects, an)rthing concerning the cause, except that it is a cause adequate to produce those effects ? It may, there- fore, safely be laid down as a truth both obvious in itself, and admitted by all whom it is at present necessary to take into consideration, that, of the outward world, we know and can know absolutely nothing, except the sensa- tions which we experience from it.f § 8. Body having now been defined the external cause, and (according to which was adopted and followed up by James Mill, has been further and greatly improved upon in Professor Bain's pro- found work. The Senses and the Intellect, and in the chapters on " Perception " o£ a work of eminent analytic power, Mr. Herbert Spencer's Principles of P»ycho- On this point M. Cousin may again be cited in favour of the better df.ctiine. M. Cousin recognises, in opposition to Reid, the essential subjectivity of our concep- tions of what are called the primary quaU- ties of matter, as extension, solidity, &c., equally with those of colour, heat, and the remainder of the so-called secondary quali- ties.—Cowri, ut supra, gme IcQon. t This doctrine, which is the most com. plete form of the philosophical theory known as the Relativity of Human Know- ledge, has, since the recent revival in this country of an active interest in metaphy- sical speculation, been the subject of a greatly increased amount of discussion and controversy ; and dissentients have mani- fested themselves in considt-rably gieater number than I had any knowledge of when the passage in the text was written. The doctrine has been attacked from two sides. Some thinkers, among whom are the late Professor Ferrier, in his Institutes of Meta- physic, and Professor John Grote, in his Erploratio Philosophica, appear to deny altogether the reality of Noumena, or Things in themselves — of an unknowable substratum or support for the sensations which we experience, and which, according to the theory, constitute all our knowledge of an external -world. It seems to me, however, that in Professor Grote's case at least, the denial of Noumena is only ap- parent, and that he does not essentially differ from the other class of objectors, in- cluding Mr. Bailey in his valuable Letters on the Philosophy of the Human Mind, and (in spite ot the striking passage quoted in the text) also Sir William Hamilton, who contend for a direct knowledge by the human mind of more than the sensations — of certain attributes or properties as they 40 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. the more reasonable opinion) the un- known external cause, to which we re- fer our sensations ; it remains to frame a definition of Mind. Nor, after the preceding observations, will this be difficult. For, as our conception of a body is that of an unknown exciting cause of sensations, so our conception of a mind is that of an unknown recipient, or percipient, of them ; and not of them alone, but of all our other feelings. As body is under- stood to be the mysterious something which excites the mind to feel, so mind is the mysterious something which feels and thinks. It is un- necessary to give in the case of mind, as we gave in the case of matter, a particular statement of the sceptical system by which its existence as a Thing in itself, distinct from the series of what are denominated its states, is called in question. But it is necessary to remark, that on the inmost nature (whatever be meant by inmost nature) of the thinking principle, as well as on the inmost nature of matter, we are, and with our faculties must always remain, entirely in the dark. All which we are aware of, even in our own minds, is (in the words of exist not in us, but in the Things them- selves. With the first of these opinions, that which denies Noumena, I have, as a meta- physician, no quarrel ; but whether it be true or false, it is irrelevant to Logic. And since all the forms of language are in con- tradiction to it, nothing but confusion could result from its unnecessary intro- duction into a treatise, every essential doc- trine of which could stand equally well with the opposite and accredited opinion. The other and rival doctrine, that of a direct perception or intuitive knowledge of the outward object as it is in itself, con- sidered as distinct from the sensations we receive from it, is of far greater practical moment. But even this question, depend- ing on the nature and laws of Intuitive Knowledge, is not within the province of Logic. For the grounds of my own opinion concerning it, I must content myself with referring to a work already mentioned — An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy: several chapters of which are devoted to a full discussion of the questions and theories relating to the supposed direct perception of external objects. James Mill) a certain "thread of consciousness ; " a series of feelings, that is, of sensations, thoughts, emo- tions, and volitions, more or less numerous and complicated. There is something I call Myself, or, by another form of expression, my mind, which I consider as distinct from these sensations, thoughts, &c. ; a something which I conceive to be not the thoughts, but the being that has the thoughts, and which I can con- ceive as existing for ever in a state of quiescence, without any thoughts at all. But what this being is, though it is myself, I have no knowledge, other than the series of its states of consciousness. As bodies manifest themselves to me only through the sensations of which I regard them as the causes, so the thinking principle, or mind, in my own nature, makes itself known to me only by the feel- ings of which it is conscious. I know nothing about myself, save my capacities of feeling or being conscious (including, of course, thinking and willing) : and were I to learn any- thing new concerning my own nature, I cannot with my present faculties conceive this new information to be anything else, than that I have some additional capacities, as yet unknown to me, of feeling, thinking, or willing. Thus, then, as body is the unsen- tient cause to which we are naturally prompted to refer a certain portion of our feelings, so mind may be described as the sentient subject (in the scholastic sense of the term) of all feelings ; that which has or feels them. But of the nature of either body or mind, further than the feelings which the former excites, and which the latter experi- ences, we do not, according to the best existing doctrine, know any- thing ; and if anything, logic has nothing to do with it, or with the manner in which the knowledge is acquired. "With this result we may conclude this portion of our subject, and pass to the third and only re- maining class or division of Nameable Things. THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES 41 III. Attributes, and, first, Qualities. § 9. From what has already been said of Substance, what is to be said of Attribute is easily deducible. For if we know not, and cannot know, anything of bodies but the sensa- tions which they excite in us or in others, those sensations must be all that we can, at bottom, mean by their attributes ; and the distinction which we verbally make between the properties of things and the sensations we receive from them, must originate in the convenience of discourse rather than in the nature of what is signified by the terms. Attributes are usually distributed under the three heads of Quality, Quantity, and Relation. We shall come to the two latter presently : in the first place we shall confine our- selves to the former. Let us take, then, as our example, one of what are termed the sensible qualities of objects, and let that example be whiteness. When we ascribe whiteness to any substance, as, for instance, snow ; when we say that snow has the quality whiteness, what do we really assert ? Simply, that when snow is present to our organs, we have a particular sensa- tion, which we are accustomed to call the sensation of white. But how do I know that snow is present ? Obvi- ously by the sensations which I derive from it, and not otherwise. I infer that the object is present, because it gives me a certain assemblage or series of sensations. And when I ascribe to it the attribute whiteness, my meaning is only, that, of the sensations composing this group or series, that which I call the sensation of white colour is one. This is one view which may be taken of the subject. But there is also another and a different view. It may be said, that it is true we know nothing of sensible objects, except the sensations they excite in us; that the fact of our receiving from snow the particular sensation which is called a sensation of white, is the ground on which we ascribe to that substance the quality whiteness ; the sole proof of its possessing that quality. But because one thing may be the sole evidence of the existence of another thing, it does not follow that the two are one and the same. The attribute whiteness (it may be said) is not the fact of receiving the sensation, but something in the object itself ; a power inherent in it ; some- thing in virtue of which the object produces the sensation. And when we affirm that snow possesses the attribute whiteness, we do not merely assert that the presence of snow pro- duces in us that sensation, but that it does so through, and by reason of, that power or quality. For the purposes of logic it is not of material importance which of these opinions we adopt. The full discus- sion of the subject belongs to the other department of scientific en- quiry, so often alluded to under the name of metaphysics ; but it may be said here, that for the doctrine of the existence of a peculiar species of entities called qualities, I can see no foundation except in a tendency of the human mind which is the cause of many delusions. I mean, the dis- position, wherever we meet with two names which are not precisely synony- mous, to suppose that they must be the names of two different things ; whereas in reality they may be names of the same thing viewed in two dif- ferent lights, or under different sup- positions as to surrounding circum- stances. Because quality and sensation cannot be put indiscriminately one for the other, it is supposed that they cannot both signify the same thing, namely, the impression or feeling with which we are affected through our senses by the presence of an object ; though there is at least no absurdity in supposing that this identical im- pression or feeling may be called a sensation when considered merely in itself, and a quality when looked at in relation to any one of the numerous 42 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. objects, the presence of which to our organs excites in our minds that among various other sensations or feelings. And if this be admissible as a supposition, it rests with those who contend for an entity per se called a quality, to show that their opinion is preferable, or is anything in fact but a lingering remnant of the old doctrine of occult causes : the very absurdity which Moliere so happily ridiculed when he made one of his pedantic physicians account for the fact that opium produces sleep by the maxim, Because it has a soporific virtue. It is evident that when the physician stated that opium has a soporific virtue, he did not account for, but merely asserted over again, the fact that it produces sleep. In like manner, when we say that snow is white because it has the quality of whiteness, we are only re-asserting in more technical language the fact that it excites in us the sensation of white. If it be said that the sensation must have some cause, I answer, its cause is the presence of the assemblage of phenomena which is termed the object. When we have asserted that as often as the object is present, and our organs in their normal state, the sensation takes place, we have stated all that we know about the matter. There is no need, after assigning a certain and intelligible cause, to suppose an occult cause besides, for the purpose of enabling the real cause to produce its effect. If I am asked, why does the presence of the object cause this sensation in me, I cannot tell : I can only say that such is my nature, and the nature of the object ; that the fact forms a part of the con- stitution of things. And to this we must at last come, even after inter- polating the imaginary entity. What- ever number of links the chain of causes and effects may consist of, how any one link pBoduces the one which is next to it, remains equally inex- plicable to us. It is as easy to com- prehend that the object should pro- duce the sensation directly and at. once, as that it should produce the same sensation by the aid of some- thing else called the power of produc- ing it. But, as the difficulties which may be felt in adopting this view of the subject cannot be removed without discussions transcending the bounds of our science, I content myself with a passing indication, and shall, for the purposes of logic, adopt a language compatible with either view of the nature of qualities. I shall say, — what at least admits of no dispute, — that the quality of whiteness ascribed to the object snow, is grounded on its exciting in us the sensation of white ; and adopting the language already used by the school logicians in the case of the kind of attributes called Relations, I shall term the sensation of white the foundation of the quality whiteness. For logical purposes the sensation is the only essential part of what is meant by the word ; the only part which we ever can be concerned in proving. When that is proved, the quality is proved ; if an object ex- cites a sensation, it has, of course, the power of exciting it. rv. Relahons. § 10. The qualities of a body, we have said, are the attributes grounded on the sensations which the presence of that particular body to our organs excites in our minds. But when we ascribe to any object the kind of attribute called a Relation, the founda- tion of the attribute must be something in which other objects are concerned besides itself and the percipient. As there may with propriety be said to be a relation between any two things to which two correlative names are or may be given, we may expect to discover what constitutes a relation in general, if we enumerate the principal cases in which mankind have imposed correlative names, and observe what these cases have in common. What, then, is the character which THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 43 is possessed in common by states of circumstances so heterogeneous and discordant as these : one thing like another ; one thing unlike ant)ther ; one thing near another ; one thing far from another ; one thing before, after, along with another ; one thing greater, equaJ, less, than another ; one thing the cause of another, the effect of another ; one person the master, ser- vant, child, parent, debtor, creditor, sovereign, subject, attorney, client, of another, and so on ? Omitting, for the present, the case of Resemblance, (a relation which requires to be considered separately,) there seems to be one thing common to all these cases, and only one ; that in each of them there exists or occurs, or has existed or occurred, or may be expected to exist or occur, some fact or phenomenon, into which the two things which are said to be related to each other, both enter as parties con- cerned. This fact, or phenomenon, is what the Aristotelian logicians called the fundamentum relationis. Thus in the relation of greater and less between two magnitudes, the fundamentum relationis is the fact that one of the two magnitudes could, under certain conditions, be included in, without entirely filling, the space occupied by the other magnitude. In the relation of master and servant, the fundamentum relationis is the fact that the one has undertaken, or is compelled, to perform certain services for the benefit and at the bidding of the other. Examples might be inde- finitely multiplied ; but it is already obvious that whenever two things are said to be related, there is some fact, or series of facts, into which they both enter : and that whenever any two things are involved in some one fact, or series of facts, we may ascribe to those two things a mutual relation grounded on the fact. Even if they have nothing in common but what is common to all things, that they are members of the universe, we call that a relation, and denominate them fellow-creatures, fellow-beings, or fel- low-denizens of the universe. But in proportion as the fact into which the two objects enter as parts is of a more special and peculiar, or of a more complicated nature, so also is the rela- tion grounded upon it. And there are as many conceivable relations as there are conceivable kinds of facts in which two things can be jointly concerned. In the same manner, therefore, as a quality is an attribute grounded on the fact that a certain sensation or sensations are produced in us by the object, so an attribute grounded on some fact into which the object enters jointly with another object, is a rela- tion between it and that other object. But the fact in the latter case consists of the very same kind of elements as the fact in the former ; namely, states of consciousness. In the case, for example, of any legal relation, as debtor and creditor, principal and agent, guardian and ward, the fun- damentum relationis consists entirely of thoughts, feelings, and volitions (actual or contingent), either of the persons themselves or of other persons concerned in the same series of trans- actions ; as, for instance, the inten- tions which would be formed by a judge, in case a complaint were made to his tribunal of the infringement of any of the legal obligations imposed by the relation ; and the acts which the judge would perform in consequence ; acts being (as we have already seen) another word for intentions followed by an effect, and that effect being but another word for sensations, or some other feelings, occasioned either to the agent himself or to somebody else. There is no part of what the names expressive of the relation imply, that is not resolvable into states of con- sciousness ; outward objects being, no doubt, supposed throughout as the causes by which some of those states of consciousness are excited, and minds as the subjects by which all of them are experienced, but neither the external objects nor the minds making their existence known otherwise than by the states of consciousness. 44 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. Oases of relation are not always so complicated as those to which we last alluded. The simplest of all cases of relation are those expressed by the words antecedent and consequent, and by the word simultaneous. If we say, for instance, that dawn pre- ceded sunrise, the fact in which the two things, dawn and sunrise, were jointly concerned, consisted only of the two things themselves ; no third thing entered into the fact or pheno- menon at all. Unless, indeed, we choose to call the succession of the two objects a third thing ; but their succession is not something added to the things themselves ; it is something involved in them. Dawn and sunrise announce themselves to our conscious- ness by two successive sensations. Our consciousness of the succession of these sensations is not a third sen- sation or feeling added to them ; we have not first the two feelings, and then a feeling of their succession. To have two feelings at all, implies hav- ing them either successively, or else simultaneously. Sensations, or other feelings, being given, succession and simultaneousness are the two condi- tions, to the alternative of which they are subjected by the nature of our faculties ; and no one has been able, or needs expect, to analyse the matter any farther. § II. In a somewhat similar posi- tion are two other sorts of relations, Likeness and TJnlikeness. I have two sensations ; we will suppose them to be simple ones ; two sensations of white, or one sensation of white and another of black. I call the first two sensations like ; the last two unlike. What is the fact or phenomenon con- stituting the fundamentum of this relation ? The two sensations first, and then what we call a feeling of resemblance, or of want of resem- blance. Let us confine ourselves to the former case. Resemblance is evi- dently a feeling ; a state of the con- sciousness of the observer. Whether the feeling of the resemblance of the two colours be a third state of con- sciousness, which I have after having the two sensations of colour, or whether (like the feeling of their succession) it is involved in the sensations them- selves, may be a matter of discussion. But in either case, these feelings of resemblance, and of its opposite dis- similarity, are parts of our nature ; and parts so far from being capable of analysis, that they are pre-supposed in every attempt to analyse any of our other feelings. Likeness and unlike- ness, therefore, as well as antecedence, sequence, and simultaneousness, must stand apart among relations, as things sui generis. They are attributes grounded on facts, that is, on states of consciousness, but on states which are peculiar, unresolvable, and inex- plicable. But, though likeness or unlikeness cannot be resolved into anything else, complex cases of likeness or unlikeness can be resolved into simpler ones. When we say of two things which consist of parts, that they are like one another, the likeness of the wholes does admit of analysis ; it is com- pounded of likenesses between the various parts respectively, and of like- ness in their arrangement. Of how vast a variety of resemblances of parts must that resemblance be composed, which induces us to say that a portrait, or a landscape, is like its original. If one person mimics another with any success, of how many simple like- nesses must the general or complex likeness be compounded : likeness in a succession of bodily postures ; like- ness in voice, or in the accents and intonations of the voice ; likeness in the choice of words, and in the thoughts or sentiments expressed, whether by word, countenance, or gesture. All likeness and unlikeness of which we have any cognizance, resolve them- selves into likeness and unlikeness between states of our own, or some other, mind. When we say that one body is like another, (since we know nothing of bodies but the sensations THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 45 which they excite,) we mean really that there is a resemblance between the sensations excited by the two bodies, or between some portions at least of those sensations. If we say that two attributes are like one another, (since we know nothing of attributes except the sensations or states of feel- ing on which they are grounded,) we mean really that those sensations, or states of feeling, resemble each other. We may also say that two relations are alike. The fact of resemblance between relations is sometimes called analogy, forming one of the numerous meanings of that word. The relation in which Priam stood to Hector, namely, that of father and son, re- sembles the relation in which Philip stood to Alexander ; resembles it so closely that they are called the same relati(m. The relation in which Cromwell stood to England resembles the relation in which Napoleon stood to France, though not so closely as to be called the same relation. The meaning in both these instances must be, that a resemblance existed between the facts which constituted the funda- mentum relationis. This resemblance may exist in all conceivable gradations, from perfect undistinguishableness to something extremely slight. When we say, that a thought suggested to the mind of a person of genius is like a seed cast into the ground because the former pro- duces a multitude of other thoughts, and the latter a multitude of other seeds, this is saying that between the relation of an inventive mind to a thought contained in it, and the rela- tion of a fertile soil to a seed contained in it, there exists a resemblance : the real resemblance being in the two fundamerda relationis, in each of which there occurs a germ, producing by its development a multitude of other things similar to itself. And as, whenever two objects are jointly con- cerned in a phenomenon, this consti- tutes a relation between those objects, so, if we suppose a second pair of objects concerned in a second pheno- menon, the slightest resemblance be- tween the two phenomena is suflBcient to admit of its being said that the two relations resemble ; provided, of course, the points of resemblance are found in those portions of the two phenomena respectively which are connoted by the relative names. While speaking of resem.blance, it is necessary to take notice of an ambiguity of language, against which scarcely any one is sufficiently on his guard. Resemblance, when it exists in the highest degree of all, amounting to'undistinguishableness, is often called identity, and the two similar things are said to be the same. I say often, not always ; for we do not say that two visible objects, two persons for in- stance, are the same, because they are so much alike that one might be mis- taken for the other : but we constantly use this mode of expression when speaking of feeling ; as when I say that the sight of any object gives me the same sensation or emotion to- day that it did yesterday, or the same which it gives to some other person. This is evidently an incorrect appli- cation of the word same; for the feeling which I had yesterday is gone, never to return ; what I have to-day is another feeling, exactly like the former perhaps, but distinct from it ; and it is evident that two different persons cannot be experiencing the same feeling, in the sense in which we say that they are both sitting at the same table. By a similar am- biguity we say, that two persons are ill of the same disease ; that two persons hold the same ofBce ; not in the sense in which we say that they are engaged in the same adventure, or sailing in the same ship, but in the sense that they fill offices exactly similar, though, perhaps, in distant places. Great confusion of ideas is often produced, and many fallacies engendered, in otherwise enlightened understandings, by not being suffi- ciently alive to the fact, (in itself not always to be avoided,) that they use the same name to express ideas sq 46 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. different as those' of identity and un- distinguishable resemblance. Among modern writers, Archbishop Whately stands almost alone in having drawn attention to this distinction, and to the ambiguity connected with it. Several relations, generally called by other names, are really cases of re- semblance. As, for example, equality ; which is but another word for the exact resemblance commonly called identity, considered as subsisting be- tween things in respect of their quantity. And this example forms a suitable transition to the third and last of the three heads under which, as already remarked, Attributes are commonly arranged. V. QUANTITT. § 12. Let us imagine two things, between which there is no difference, (that is, no dissimilarity,) except in quantity alone : for instance, a gallon of water, and more than a gallon of water. A gallon of water, like any other external object, makes its pre- sence known to us by a set of sensa- tions which it excites. Ten gallons of water are also an external object, making its presence known to us in a similar manner ; and as we do not mistake ten gallons of water for a gallon of water, it is plain that the set of sensations is more or less dif- ferent in the two cases. In like manner, a gallon of water, and a gallon of wine, are two external objects, making their presence known by two sets of sensations, which sensa- tions are different from each other. In the first case, however, we say that the difference is in quantity ; in the last there is a difference in quality, while the quantity of the water and of the wine is the same. What is the real distinction between the two cases ? It is not within the province of Logic to analyse it ; nor to decide whether it is susceptible of analysis or not. For us the following considerations are sufficient. It is evident that the geusations I receive from the gallon of water, and those I received from the gallon of wine, are not the same, that is, not precisely alike ; neither are they altogether unlike : they are partly similar, partly dissimilar ; and that in which they resemble is pre- cisely that in which alone the gallon of water and the ten gallons do not resemble. That in which the gallon of water and the gallon of wine are like each other, and in which the gallon and the ten gallons of water are unlike each other, is called their quantity. This likeness and unlike- ness I do not pretend to explain, no more than any other kind of likeness or unlikeness. But my object is to show, that when we say of two things that they differ in quantity, just as when we say that they differ in quality, the assertion is always grounded on a difference in the sen- sations which they excite. Nobody, I presume, will say, that to see, or to lift, or to drink, ten gallons of water, does not include in itself a different set of sensations from those of seeing, lifting, or drinking one gallon ; or that to see or handle a foot-rule, and to see or handle a yard-measure made exactly like it, are the same sensations. I do not undertake to say what the difference in the sensations is. Every- body knows, and nobody can tell ; no more than any one could tell what white is to a person who had never had the sensation. But the differ- ence, so far as cognizable by our faculties, lies in the sensations. Whatever difference we say there is in the things themselves, is in this, as in all other cases, grounded, and grounded exclusively, on a difference in the sensations excited by them. YI. Attributes Concluded. § 13. Thus, then, all the attri- butes of bodies which are classed under Quality or Quantity, are grounded on the sensations which we received from those bodies, and may be defined, the powers which the boclies have of exciting those scR' THINGS DENOTED BY NAMES. 47 sations. And the same general ex- planation has been found to apply to most of the attributes usually classed under the head of Relation. They, too, are grounded on some fact or phenomenon into which the related objects enter as parts ; that fact or phenomenon having no meaning and no existence to us, except the series of sensations or other states of conscious- ness by which it makes itself known ; and the relation being simply the power or capacity which the object posgesses of taking part along with the correlated object in the production of that series of sensations or states of consciousness. We have been obliged indeed, to recognise a some- what different character in certain peculiar relations, those of succession and simultaneity, of likeness and un- likeness. These, not being grounded on any fact or phenomenon distinct from the related objects themselves, do not admit of the same kind of analysis. But these relations, though not, like other relations, grounded on states of consciousness, are themselves states of consciousness : resemblance is nothing but our feeling of resem- blance ; succession is nothing but our feeling of succession. Or, if this be disputed, (and we cannot, without transgressing the bounds of our science, discuss it here,) at least our knowledge of these relations, and even our possibility of knowledge, is con- fined to those which subsist between sensations, or other states of con- sciousness ; for, though we ascribe resemblance, or succession, or simul- taneity, to objects and to attributes, it is always in virtue of resemblance or succession or simultaneity in the sensations or states of consciousness which those objects excite, and on which those attributes are grounded. § 14. In the preceding investigation we have, for the sake of simplicity, considered bodies only, and omitted minds. But what we have said is applicable, mutatis mutandis, to the latter. The attributes of minds, as well as those of bodies, are grounded on states of feeling or consciousness. But in the case of a miiid, we have to consider its own states, as well as those which it produces in other minds. Every attribute of a mind consists either in being itself affected in a certain way, or affecting other minds in a certain way. Considered in itself, we can predicate nothing of it but the series of its own feelings. When we say of any mind, that it is devout, or superstitious, or meditative, or cheerful, we mean that the ideas, emotions, or volitions implied in those words, form a frequently recurring part of the series of feelings, or states of consciousness, which fill up the sentient existence of that mind. In addition, however, to those attri- butes of a mind which are grounded on its own states of feeling, attributes may also be ascribed to it, in the same manner as to a body, grounded on the feelings which it excites in other minds. A mind does not, indeed, like a body, excite sensations, but it may excite thoughts or emotions. The most important example of attri- butes ascribed on this ground, is the employment of terms expressive of approbation or blame. When, for example, we say of any character, or (in other words) of any mind, that it is admirable, we mean that the con- templation of it excites the sentiment of admiration ; and indeed somewhat more, for the word implies that we not only feel admiration, but approve that sentiment in ourselves. In some cases, under the semblance of a single attribute, two are really predicated : one of them, a state of the mind it- self; the other, a state with which other minds are affected by thinking of it. As when we say of any one that he is generous. The word gene- rosity expresses a certain state of mind, but being a term of praise, it also ex- presses that this state of mind excites in us another mental state, called approbation. The assertion made, therefore, is twofold, and of the fol- lowing purport : Certain feelings form 48 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. habitually a part of this person's sentient existence ; and the idea of those feelings of his, excites the senti- ment of approbation in ourselves or others. As we thus ascribe attributes to minds on the ground of ideas and emotions, so may we to bodies on similar grounds, and not solely on the ground of sensations : as in speaking of the beauty of a statue ; since this attribute is grounded on the peculiar feeling of pleasure which the statue produces in our minds ; which is not a sensation, but an emotion. YTT. Geneeal Kesults. § 15. Our survey of the varieties of Things which have been, or which are capable of being, named — which have been, or are capable of being, either predicated of other Things, or them- selves made the subject of predica- tions— is now concluded. Our enumeration commenced with Feelings. These we scrupulously dis- tinguished from the objects which excite them, and from the organs by which they are, or may be supposed to be, conveyed. Feelings are of four sorts : Sensations, Thoughts, Emotions, and Volitions. What are called Perceptions are merely a par- ticular case of Belief, and belief is a kind of thought. Actions are merely volitions followed by an effect. After Feelings we proceeded to Substances. These are either Bodies or Minds. Without entering into the grounds of the metaphysical doubts which have been raised con- cerning the existence of Matter and Mind as objective realities, we stated as sufficient for us the conclusion in which the best thinkers are now for the most part agreed, that all we can know of Matter is the sensations which it gives us, and the order of occurrence of those sensations ; and that while the substance Body is the unknown cause of our sensations, the substance Mind is the unknown re- cipient. The only remaining class of Name- able Things is attributes ; and these are of three kinds, Quality, Relation, and Quantity. Qualities, like sub- stances, are known to us no otherwise than by the sensations or other states of consciousness which they excite : and while, in compliance with com- mon usage, we have continued to speak of them as a distinct class of Things, we showed that in predicating them no one means to predicate any- thing but those sensations or states of consciousness, on which they may be said to be grounded, and by which alone they can be defined or described. Relations, except the simple cases of likeness and unlikeness, succession and simultaneity, are similarly grounded on some fact or phenomenon, that is, on some series of sensations or states of consciousness, more or less complicated. The third species of Attribute, Quantity, is also mani- festly grounded on something in our sensations or states of feeling, since there is an indubitable difference in the sensations excited by a larger and a smaller bulk, or by a greater or a less degree of intensity, in any object of sense or of consciousness. All attributes, therefore, are to us nothing but either our sensations and other states of feeling, or something inex- tricably involved therein ; and to this even the peculiar and simple relations just adverted to are not exceptions. Those peculiar relations, however, are so important, and, even if they might in strictness be classed among states of consciousness, are so fundamentally distinct from any other of those states, that it would be a vain subtlety to bring them under that common description, and it is necessary that they should be classed apart.* * Professor Bain {Logic, i. 45) defines attributes as "points of community among classes." This definition expresses well one point of view, but is liable to the objection that it applies only to the attri- butes of classes ; though an object, unique in its kind, may be said to have attributes. Moreover, the definition is not ultimate, since the points of community themselves PROPOSITIONS. 49 As the result, therefore, of our analysis, we obtain the following as an enumeration and classification of all Nameable Things : — 1st. Feelings, or States of Con- sciousness. 2nd. The Minds which experience those feelings. 3rd. The Bodies, or external objects which excite certain of those feelings, together with the powers or properties whereby they excite them ; these latter (at least) being included rather in compliance with common opinion, and because their existence is taken for granted in the common language from which I cannot prudently deviate, than because the recognition of such powers or properties as real existences appears to be warranted by a sound philosoph}'. 4th, and last. The Successions and Co-existences, the Likenesses and Un- likenesses, between feelings or states of consciousness. Those relations, when considered as subsisting be- tween other things, exist in reality only between the states of consciousness which those things, if bodies, excite, if minds, either excite or experience. This, until a better can be sug- gested, may serve as a substitute for the Categories of Aristotle considered as a Classification of Existences. The practical application of it will appear when we commence the in- quiry into the Import of Proposi- tions ; in other words, when we in- quire what it is which the mind actually believes when it gives what is called its assent to a proposition. These four classes comprising, if the classification be correct, all Nameable Things, these or some of them must of course compose the signification of all names ; and of these, or some of them, is made up whatever we call a fact. For distinction's sake, every fact which is solely composed of feelings admit of, and require, further analysis; and Mr. Bain does analyse them into re- semblance in the sensations, or other states of consciousness excited by the object. or states of consciousness considered as such, is often called a Psychological or Subjective fact ; while every fact which is composed, either wholly or in part, of something dififerent from these, that is, of substances and attributes, is called an Objective fact. We may say, then, that every ob- jective fact is grounded on a corre- sponding siibjective one ; and has no meaning to us, (apart from the sub- jective fact which corresponds to it,) except as a name for the unknown and inscrutable process by which that subjective or psychological fact is brought to pass. CHAPTER IV. OP PROPOSITIONS. § I. In treating of Propositions, as already in treating of Names, some considerations of a comparatively elementary nature respecting their form and varieties must be premised, before entering upon that analysis of the import conveyed by them, which is the real subject and purpose of this preliminary book. A proposition, we have before said, is a portion of discourse in which a predicate is aflBrmed or denied of a sub- ject. A predicate and a subject are all that is necessarily required to make up a proposition : but as we cannot con- clude from merely seeing two names put together, that they are a pre- dicate and a subject, that is, that one of them is intended to be affirmed or denied of the other, it is necessary that there should be some mode or form of indicating that such is the intention ; some sign to distinguish a predication from any other kind of discourse. This is sometimes done by a slight alteration of one of the words, called an ivflection; as when we say. Fire burns ; the change of the second word from hum to hums showing that we mean to affirm the predicate burn of the subject fire. But this function is more commonly so NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. fulfilled by the word is, when an affirmation is intended, is not, when a negation ; or by some other part of the verb to be. The word which thus serves the purpose of a sign of predica- tion is called, as we formerly observed, the copula. It is important that there should be no indistinctness in our conception of the nature and office of the copula ; for confused notions respecting it are among the causes which have spread mysticism over the field of logic, and perverted its speculations into logomachies. It is apt to be supposed that the copula is something more than a mere sign of predication ; that it also signifies existence. In the proposi- tion, Socrates is just, it may seem to be implied not only that the quality just can be affirmed of Socrates, but moreover that Socrates is, that is to say, exists. This, however, only shows that there is an ambiguity in the word is ; a word which not only performs the function of the copula in affirma- tions, but has also a meaning of its own, in virtue of which it may itself be made the predicate of a proposi- tion. That the employment of it as a copula does not necessarily include the affirmation of existence, appears from such a proposition as this : A centaur is a fiction of the poets ; where it cannot possibly be implied that a centaur exists, since the proposition itself expressly asserts that the thing has no real existence. Many volumes might be filled with the frivolous speculations concerning the nature of Being, (tto 6v, ovaia. Ens, Entitas, Essentia, and the like,) which have arisen from overlooking this double meaning of the word to he; from supposing that when it signifies to exist, and when it signifies to he some specified thing, as to he a man, to he Socrates, to he seen or spoken of, io he a phantom, even to he a nonentity, it must still, at bottom, answer to the same idea ; and that a meaning must be found for it which shall suit all these cases. The fog '\yhich rose from this narrow spot diffused itself at an early period over the whole surface of metaphysics. Yet it becomes us nOt to triumph over the great intellects of Plato and Aristotle because we are now able to preserve ourselves from many errors into which they, perhaps inevitably, fell. The fire-teazer of a modem steam-engine produces by his exer- tions far greater effects than Milo of Crotona could, but he is not there- fore a stronger man. The Greeks seldom knew .any language but their own. This rendered it far more difficult for them than it is for us, to acquire a readiness in detecting ambiguities. One of the advantages of having accurately studied a plurality of languages, especially of those languages which eminent thinkers have used as the vehicle of their thoughts, is the practical lesson we learn respecting the ambiguities of words, by finding that the same word in one language corresponds, on dif- ferent occasions, to different words in another. When not thus exercised, even the strongest understandings find it difficult to believe that things which have a common name have not in some respect or other a common nature ; and often expend much labour very unprofitably (as was frequently done by the two philo- sophers just mentioned) in vain attempts to discover in what this common nature consists. But, the habit once formed, intellects much inferior are capable of detecting even ambiguities which are common to many languages : and it is surprising that the one now under consideration, though it exists in the modern lan- guages as well as in the ancient, should have been overlooked by almost all authors. The quantity of futile speculation which had been caused by a misapprehension of the nature of the copula was hinted at by Hobbes ; but Mr. James Mill * was, I believe, the first who distinctly characterized the ambiguity, and * Analysis of the Human Mind, i. 126 et seq. PROPOSITIONS. 51 pointed out how many errors in the received systems of philosophy it has had to answer for. It has indeed misled the modems scarcely less than the ancients, though their mistakes, because our understandings are not yet so completely emancipated from their influence, do not appear equally irrational. We shall now briefly review the principal distinctions which exist among propositions, and the technical terms most commonly in use to ex- press those distinctions. § 2. A proposition being a portion of discourse in which something is affirmed or denied of something, the first division of propositions is into affirmative and negative. An affir- mative proposition is that in which the predicate is affirmed of the subject ; as, Caesar is dead. A negative pro- position is that in which the predicate is denied of the subject ; as, Caesar is not dead. The copula, in this last species of proposition, consists of the words is not, which are the sign of negation ; is being the sign of affir- mation. Some logicians, among whom may be mentioned Hobbes, state this dis- tinction differently ; they recognise only one form of copula, is, and attach the negative sign to the predicate. " Caesar is dead," and " Caesar is not dead," according to these writers, are propositions agreeing not in the sub- ject and predicate, but in the subject only. They do not consider " dead," but " not dead," to be the predicate of the second proposition, and they ac- cordingly define a negative proposition to be one in which the predicate is a negative name. The point, though not of much practical moment, de- serves notice as an example (not un- frequent in logic) where by means of an apparent simplification, but which is merely verbal, matters are made more complex than before. The notion of these writers was, that they could get rid of the distinction between affirming and denying, by treating every case of denying as the affirming of a negative name. But what is meant by a negative name ? A name expressive of the absence of an attri- bute. So that when we affirm a nega- tive name, what we are really predi- cating is absence and not presence ; we are asserting not that anything is, but that something is not ; to express which operation no word seems so proper as the word denying. The fundamental distinction is between a fact and the non-existence of that fact ; between seeing something and not seeing it, between Caesar's being dead and his not being dead ; and if this were a merely verbal distinction, the generalization which brings both within the same form of assertion would be a real simplification : the distinction, however, being real, and in the facts, it is the generalization confounding the distinction that is merely verbal ; and tends to obscure the subject, by treating the difference between two kinds of truths as if it were only a difference between two kinds of words. To put things to- gether, and to put them or keep them asunder, will remain different opera- tions, whatever tricks we may play with language. A remark of a similar nature may be applied to most of those distinc- tions among propositions which are said to have reference to their mo- dality; as, difference of tense or time ; the sun did rise, the sun is rising, the sun will rise. These differences, like that between affirmation and nega- tion, might be glossed over by con- sidering the incident of time as a mere modification of the predicate : thus, The sun is an object having risen, The sun is an object now rising, The sun is an object to rise Tiei'eafter. But the simplification would be merely verbal. Past, present, and futiire, do not con- stitute so many different kinds of rising ; they are designations belong- ing to the event asserted, to the sun's rising to day. They affect, not the predicate, but the applicability of the predicate to the particular subject. s» NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. That which we affirm to be past, present, or future, is not what the subject signifies, nor what the predi- cate signifies, but specifically and ex- pressly what the predication signifies ; what is expressed only by the proposi- tion as such, and not by either or both of the terms. Therefore the circumstance of time is properly con- sidered as attaching to the copula, which is the sign of predication, and not to the predicate. If the same cannot be said of such modifications as these, Caesar may be dead ; Caesar is perhaps dead ; it is possible that Caesar is dead ; it is only because these fall altogether under another head, being properly assertions not of anything relating to the fact itself, but of the state of our own mind in regard to it ; namely, our absence of disbelief of it. Thus " Caesar may be dead " means '* I am not sure that Caesar is alive." § 3. The next division of proposi- tions is into Simple and Complex ; more aptly (by Professor Bain *) termed Compound. A simple pro- position is that in which one predicate is affirmed or denied of one subject. A compound proposition is that in which there is more than one predicate, or more than one subject, or both. At first sight this division has the air of an absurdity ; a solemn distinc- tion of things into one and more than one ; as if we were to divide horses into single horses and teams of horses. And it is true that what is called a complex (or compound) proposition is often not a proposition at all, but several propositions, held together by a conjunction. Such, for example, is this : Caesar is dead, and Brutus is alive : or even this, Caesar is dead, hut Brutus is alive. There are here two distinct assertions ; and we might as well call a street a complex house, as these two propositions a complex proposition. It is true that the syn- categorematic words arid and hut have * Logic, i. 8s. a meaning ; but that meaning is so far from making the two propositions one, that it adds a third proposition to them. All particles are abbrevia- tions, and generally abbreviations of propositions ; a kind of shorthand, whereby something which, to be ex- pressed fully, would have required a proposition or a series of propositions, is suggested to the mind at once. Thus the words, Cassar is dead and Brutus is alive, are equivalent to these : Caesar is dead ; Brutus is alive ; it is desired that the two pre- ceding propositions should be thought of together. If the words were, Caesar is dead, hut Brutus is alive, the sense would be equivalent to the same three propositions together with a fourth ; " between the two preceding propositions there exists a contrast : " viz. either between the two facts them« selves, or between the feelings with which it is desired that they should be regarded. In the instances cited the two pro* positions are kept visibly distinct, each subject having its separate predicate, and each predicate its separate sub- ject. For brevity, however, and to avoid repetition, the propositions are often blended together : as in this, " Peter and James preached at Jeru- salem and in Galilee," which contains four propositions : Peter preached at Jerusalem, Peter preached in Galilee, James preached at Jerusalem, James preached in Galilee. We have seen that when the two or more propositions comprised in what is called a complex proposition are stated absolutely and not under any condition or proviso, it is not a pro- position at all, but a plurality of pro- positions ; since what it expresses is not a single assertion, but several assertions, which, if true when joined, are true also when separated. But there is a kind of proposition which, though it contains a plurality of sub- jects and of predicates, and may be said in one sense of the word to con- sist of several propositions, contains but one assertion ; and its truth does PROPOSITIONS. 55 not at all imply that of the simple propositions which compose it. An example of this is, when the simple propositions are connected by the particle or ; as, either A is B or C is D ; or by the particle if ; as, A is B if C is D. In the former case, the proposition is called disjunctive, in the latter, conditional: the name hypo- thetical was originally common to both. As has been well remarked by Archbishop Whately and others, the disjunctive form is resolvable into the conditional ; every disjunctive pro- position being equivalent to two or more conditional ones. " Either A is B or C is D," means, " if A is not B, C is D ; and if C is not D, A is B." A-11 hypothetical propositions, there- fore, though disjunctive in form, are conditional in meaning ; and the words hypothetical and conditional may be, as indeed they generally are, used synonymously. Propositions in which the assertion is not dependent on a condition, are said, in the lan- guage of logicians, to be categorical. An hypothetical proposition is not, like the pretended complex proposi- tions which we previously considered, a niere aggregation of simple proposi- tions. The simple propositions which form part of the words in which it is couched, form no part of the assertion which it conveys. When we say. If the Koran comes from God, Mahomet is the prophet of God, we do not in- tend to affirm either that the Koran does come from God, or that Mahomet is really His prophet. Neither of these simple propositions may be true, and yet the truth of the hypotheti- cal proposition may be indisputable. What is asserted is not the truth of either of the propositions, but the inferribility of the one from the other. What, then, is the subject, and what the predicate of the hypothetical pro- position ? " The Koran " is not the subject of it, nor is "Mahomet: " for nothing is affirmed or denied either of the Koran or of Mahomet. The real subject of the predication is the entire proposition, *' Mahomet is the prophet of God ; " and the affirmation is, that this is a legitimate inference from the proposition, *' the Koran comes from God." The subject and predicate, therefore, of an hypothetical proposi- tion are names of propositions. The Bvibject is some one proposition. The predicate is a general relative name applicable to propositions of this form — "an inference from so and so." A fresh instance is here afforded of the remark, that particles are abbrevia- tions ; since " /f A is B, C is D," is found to be an abbreviation of the following : " The proposition C is D, is a legitimate inference from the proposition A is B." The distinction, therefore, between hypothetical and categorical proposi- tions, is not so great as it at first appears. In the conditional, as well as in the categorical form, one predi- cate is aflBrmed of one subject, and no more : but a conditional proposition is a proposition concerning a proposi- tion ; the subject of the assertion is itself an assertion. Nor is this a property peculiar to hypothetical pro- positions. There are other classes of assertions concerning propositions. Like other things, a proposition has attributes which may be predicated of it. The attribute predicated of it in an hypothetical proposition, is that of being an inference from a certain other proposition. But this is only one of many attributes that might be predicated. We may say. That the whole is greater than its part, is an axiom in mathematics : That the Holy Ghost proceeds from the Father alone, is a tenet of the Greek Church : The doctrine of the divine right of kings was renounced by Parliament at the Revolution : The infallibility of the Pope has no countenance from Scripture. In all these cases the subject of the predication is an entire proposition. That which these differ- ent predicates are affirmed of is the proposition, "the whole is greater than its part ; " the proposition, "the Holy Ghost proceeds from the Father alone ; " the proposition, kings have a 54 NAMES AND PHOPOSITIONS. divine right ; " the proposition, " the Pope is infallible." Seeing, then, that there is much less difference between hypothetical propositions and any others, than one might be led to imagine from their form, we should be at a loss to account for the conspicuous position which they have been selected to fill in treatises on logic, if he did not re- member that what they predicate of a proposition, namely, its being an in- ference from something else, is precisely that one of its attributes with which most of all a logician is concerned. § 4. The next of the common divisions of Propositions is into Uni- versal, Particular, Indefinite, and Singular : a distinction founded on the degree of generality in which the name, which is the subject of the proposition, is to be understood. The following are examples : AU men are mortal — Universal. Some men are mortal — Particular. Man is mortal — Indefinite. Julim Ccesar is mortal — Singular. The proposition is Singular when the subject is an individual name. The individual name needs not be a proper name. "The Founder of Christianity was crucified," is as much a singular proposition as " Christ was crucified." When the name which is the sub- ject of the proposition is a general name, we may intend to affirm or deny the predicate, either of all the things that the subject denotes, or only of some. When the predicate is affirmed or denied of all and each of the things denoted by the siibject, the proposition is universal ; when of some undefined portion of them only, it is particular. Thus, All men are mortal ; Every man is mortal ; are universal propositions. No man is immortal, is also an universal propo- sition, since the predicate, immortal, is denied of each and every individual denoted by the term man ; the nega- tive proposition being exactly equiva- lent to the following. Every man is not-immortal. But "some men are wise," "some men are not wise," are particular propositions ; the predicate tdse being in the one case affirmed and in the other denied not of each and every individual denoted by the term man, but only of each and every one of some portion of those indivi- duals, without specifying what por- tion ; for if this were specified, the proposition would be changed either into a singular proposition, or into an universal proposition with a different subject ; as, for instance, '^ all properly instructed men are wise, " There are other forms of particular propositions ; as, ^^ Most men are imperfectly edu- cated : " it being immaterial how large a portion of the subject the predicate is asserted of, as long as it is left un- certain how that portion is to be dis- tinguished from the rest.* When the form of expression does not clearly show whether the general name which is the subject of the pro- position is meant to stand for all the individuals denoted by it, or only for some of them, the proposition is, by some logicians, called Indefinite ; but this, as Archbishop Whately observes, is a solecism, of the same nature as that committed by some grammarians when in their list of genders they enumerate the doubtful * Instead of Universal and Particular, as applied to propositions, Professor Bain pro- poses (Logic, i. 81) the terms Total and Partial ; reserving the former pair of terms for their inductive meaninpr, " the contrast between a general proposition and the par- ticulars or iTidividuals that we derive it from." This change in nomenclature would be attended with the further advantage, that Singular propositions, which in tiie Syllogism follow the same rules as Uni- versal, would be included along with them in the same class, that of Total predica- tions. It is not the Subject's denoting many things or only one, that is of im- portance in reasoning, it is that tlu^ asser- tion is made of the whole or a part only of what the Subject denotes. The words Universal and Particular, however, are so familiar and so well understood in both the senses mentioned by Mr. Bain, that the double meaning does not produce any material inconvenience. IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 55 gender. The speaker must mean to assert the proposition either as an universal or as a particular proposi- tion, though he has failed to declare which : and it often happens that though the words do not show which of the two he intends, the context, or the custom of speech, supplies the deficiency. Thus, when it is affirmed that " Man is mortal," nobody doubts that the assertion is intended of all human beings ; and the word indi- cative of universality is commonly emitted, only because the meaning is evident without it. In the proposition, "Wine is good," it is understood with «qual readiness, though for somewhat different reasons, that the assertion ia not intended to be universal, but particular.* As is observed by Pro- fessor Bain,t the chief examples of Indefinite propositions occur "with names of material, which are the sub- jects sometimes of universal, and at other times of particular predication. 'Fcod is chemically constituted by carbon, oxygen, &c.,' is a proposition of universal quantity ; the meaning is all food — all kinds of food. * Food is necessary to animal life ' is a case of particular quantity ; the meaning is some sort of food, not necessarily all sorts. * Metal is requisite in order to strength ' does not mean all kinds of metal. 'Gold will make a way,' means a portion of gold." When a general name stands for each and every individual which it is a name of, or in other words, which it denotes, it is said by logicians to be distHbuted, or taken distributively. Thus, in the proposition. All men are mortal, the subject, Man, is dis- tributed, because mortality is aflBrmed of each and every man. The predi- cate. Mortal, is not distributed, because the only mortals who are spoken of in the proposition are those * It may, however, be considered as equivalent to an universal proposition with a different predicate, viz. "All wine is good qiid wine," or " is good in respect of the qualities which consti*iute it wine." t Logic, i. 82. who happen to be men ; while the word may, for aught that appears, and in fact does, comprehend within it an indefinite number of objects besides men. In the proposition, Some men are mortal, both the pre- dicate and the subject are undis- tributed. In the following, No men have wings, both the predicate and the subject are distributed. Not only is the attribute of having wings denied of the entire class Man, but that class is severed and cast out from the whole of the class Winged, and not merely from some part of that class. This phraseology, which is of great service in stating and demonstrating the rules of the syllogism, enables us to express very concisely the defini- tions of an universal and a particular proposition. An universal proposi- tion is that of which the subject is distributed ; a particular proposition is that of which the subject is un- distributed. There are many more distinctions among propositions than those we have here stated, some of them of considerable importance. But, for explaining and illustrating these, more suitable opportunities will occur in the sequel. CHAPTER V. OF THE IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. § I. An inquiry into the nature of propositions must have one of two objects : to analyse the state of mind called Belief, or to analyse what is believed. All language recognises a difference between a doctrine or opinion, and the fact of entertaining the opinion ; between assent, and what is assented to. Logic, according to the conception here formed of it, has no concern with the nature of the act of judging or believing; the consideration of that act, as a phenomenon of the mind, belongs to another science. 56 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. Philosophers, however, from Descartes downwards, and especially from the era of Leibnitz and Locke, have by no means observed this distinction ; and would have treated with great disrespect any attempt to analyse the import of Propositions, unless founded on an analysis of the act of Judgment. A proposition, they would have said, is but the expression in words of a Judgment. The thing expressed, not the mere verbal expression, is the important matter. When the mind assents to a proposition, it judges. Let us find out what the mind does when it judges, and we shall know what propositions mean, and not otherwise. Conformably to these views, almost all the writers on Logic in the last two centuries, whether English, Ger- man, or French, have made their theory of Propositions, from one end to the other, a theory of Judgments. They considered a Proposition, or a Judgment, for they used the two words indiscriminately, to consist in affirming or denying one idea of another. To judge, was to put two ideas together, or to bring one idea under another, or to compare two ideas, or to perceive the agreement or disagreement between two ideas : and the whole doctrine of Proposi- tions, together with the theory of Reasoning,(alwaysnecessarilyfounded on the theory of Propositions,) was stated as if Ideas, or Conceptions, or whatever other term the writer pre- ferred as a name for mental represen- tations generally, constituted essen- tially the subject-matter and substance of those operations. It is, of course, true, that in any case of judgment, as for instance when we judge that gold is yellow, a process takes place in our minds, of which some one or other of these theories is a partially correct account. We must have the idea of gold and the idea of yellow, and these two ideas must be brought together in our mind. But in the first place, it is evident that this is only a part of what takes place ; for we may put two ideas to- gether without any act of belief ; as when we merely imagine something, such as a golden mountain ; or when we actually disbelieve : for in order even to disbelieve that Mahomet was an apostle of God, we must put the idea of Mahomet and that of an apos- tle of God together. To determine what it is that happens in the case of assent or dissent besides putting two ideas together, is one of the most in- tricate of metaphysical problems. But whatever the solution may be, we may venture to assert that it can hav-e nothing whatever to do with the iai- port of propositions ; for this reason, that propositions (except sometines when the mind itself is the sulqject treated of) are not assertions respect- ing our ideas of things, but assertions respecting the things themselves. In order to believe that gold is yellow, I must, indeed, have the idea of gold, and the idea of yellow, and something having reference to those ideas must take place in my mind ; but my belief has not reference to the ideas, it has reference to the things. What I be- lieve, is a fact relating to the out^v■ard thing, gold, and to the impressiott made by that outward thing upon the human organs ; not a fact relating to my conception of gold, which would be a fact in my mental history, not a fact of external nature. It is true, that in order to believe this fact in external nature, another fact must take place in my mind, a process must be performed upon my ideas ; but so it must in everything else that I do. I cannot dig the ground unless I have the idea of the ground, and of a spade, and of all the other things I am ope- rating upon, and unless I put those ideas together.* But it would be a * Dr. Whewell (Philosophi/ of Discovery, p. 242) questions this statement, and asks, "Are we to say that a mole cannot dig the ground, except he has an idea of the ground, and of the snout and paws with which he digs it ? " I do not know what passes in a mole's mind, nor what amount of mental apprehension may or may not accompany his instinctive actions. But IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 57 very ridiculous description of digging the ground to say that it is putting one idea into another. Digging is an operation which is performed upon the things themselves, though it cannot be performed unless I have in my mind the ideas of them. And in like man- ner, believing is an act which has for its subject thefacts themselves, though a previous mental conception of the facts is an indispensable condition. When I say that fire causes heat, do I mean that my idea of fire causes my idea of heat ? No : I mean that the natural phenomenon, fire, causes the natural phenomenon, heat. When I mean to assert anything respecting the ideas, I give them their proper name ; I call them ideas ; as when I say that a child's idea of a battle is unlike the reality, or that the ideas entertained of the Deity have a great effect on the characters of mankind. The notion that what is of primary importance to the logician in a pro- position, is the relation between the two ideas corresponding to the subject and predicate, (instead of the relation between the two phenomena which they respectively express,) seems to me one of the most fatal errors ever introduced into the philosophy of Logic ; and the principal cause why the theory of the science has made Buch inconsiderable progress during the last two centuries. The treatises on Logic, and on the branches of Mental Philosophy connected with Logic, which have been produced since the intrusion of this cardinal error, though sometimes written by men of extraordinary abilities and attainments, almost always tacitly imply a theory that the investigation of truth consists in contemplating and handling our ideas, or conceptions of things, instead of the things them- selves : a doctrine tantamount to the assertion, that the only mode of ac- quiring knowledge of nature is to a human being does not use a spade by instinct ; and he certainly could not use it unless he had knowledge of a spade, and of the earth which he uses it upon. I study it at second-hand, as represented in our own minds. Meanwhile, in- quiries into every kind of natural phenomena were incessantly establish- ing great and fruitful truths on most important subjects, by processes upon I which these views of the nature of Judgment and Reasoning threw no \ light, and in which they afforded no i assistance whatever. No wonder that those who knew by practical experi- ence how truths are arrived at, should deem a science futile, which consisted chiefly of such speculations. What has been done for the advancement of Logic since these doctrines came into vogue, has been done not by pro- fessed logicians, but by discoverers in the other sciences ; in whose methods of investigation many principles of logic, not previously thought of, have successively come forth into light, but who have generally committed the error of supposing that nothing what- ever was known of the art of philoso- phizing by the old logicians, because theirmodern interpreters have written to so little purpose respecting it. We have to inquire, then, on the present occasion, not into Judgment, but judgments ; not into the act of believing, but into the thing believed. What is the immediate object of belief in a Proposition ? What is the matter of fact signified by it ? What is it to which, when I assert the proposition, I give my assent, and call upon others to give theirs ? What is that which is expressed by the form of discourse called a Proposition, and the confor- mity of which to fact constitutes the truth of the proposition ? § 2. One of the clearest and most consecutive thinkers whom this coun- try or the world has produced, I mean Hobbes, has given the following answer to this question. In every proposition (says he) what is signified is, the belief of the speaker that the predicate is a name of the same thing of which the subject is a name ; and if it really is so, the proposition is true. Thus the proposition, All men NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. are living beings (he would say) is true, because living being is a name of everything of which man is a name. All men are six feet high, is not true, because six feet high is riot a name of everything (though it is of some things) of which man is a name. What is stated in this theory as the definition of a true proposition, must be allowed to be a property which all true propositions possess. The subject and predicate being both of them names of things, if they were names of quite different things the one name could not, consistently with its signi- fication, be predicated of the other. If it be true that some men are copper- coloured, it must be true — and the proposition does really assert — that among the individuals denoted by the name man, there are some who are also among those denoted by the name copper-coloured. If it be true that all oxen ruminate, it must be true that all the individuals denoted by the name ox are also among those denoted by the name ruminating ; and whoever asserts that all oxen ruminate, undoubtedly does assert that this relation subsists between the two names. The assertion, therefore, which, according to Hobbes, is the only one made in any proposition, really is made in every proposition : and his analysis has consequently one of the requisites for being the true one. We may go a step farther ; it is the only analysis that is rigorously true of all propositions without exception. What he gives as the meaning of proposi- tions, is part of the meaning of all propositions, and the whole meaning of some. This, however, only shows what an extremely minute fragment of meaning it is quite possible to in- clude within the logical formula of a proposition. It does not show that no proposition means more. To war- rant us in putting together two words with a copula between them, it is really enough that the thing or things denoted by one of the names should be capable, without violation of usage. of being called by the other name also. If, then, this be all the meaning necessarily implied in the form of discourse called a Proposition, why do I object to it as the scientific defi- nition of what a proposition means? Because, though the mere collocation which makes the proposition a propo- sition, conveys no more than this scanty amount of meaning, that same collocation combined with other cir- cumstances, that form combined with other mutter, does convey more, and the proposition in those other circum- stances does assert more, than merely that relation between the two names. The only propositions of which Hobbes' principle is a sufficient account, are that limited and unim- portant class in which both the pre- dicate and the subject are proper names. For, as has already been remarked, proper names have strictly no meaning ; they are mere marks for individual objects : and when a pro- per name is predicated of another proper name, all the signification con- veyed is, that both the names are marks for the same object. But this is precisely what Hobbes produces as a theory of predication in general. His doctrine is a full explanation of such predications as these : Hyde was Clarendon, or, TuUy is Cicero. It exhausts the meaning of those pro- positions. But it is a sadly inadequate theory of any others. That it should ever have been thought of as such, can be accounted for only by the fact, that Hobbes, in common with the other Nominalists, bestowed little or no attention upon the connotation of words ; and sought for their meaning exclusively in what they denote : as if all names had been (what none but proper names really are) marks put upon individuals ; and as if there were no difference between a proper and a general name, except that the first denotes only one individual, and the last a greater number. It has been seen, however, that the meaning of all names, except proper names and that portion of the cUss IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 59 of abstract names which are not con- notative, resides in the connotation. When, therefore, we are analysing the meaning of any proposition in which the predicate and the subject, or either of them, are connotative names, it is to the connotation of those terms that we must exclusively look, and not to what they denote, or, in the language of Hobbes, (language so far correct,) are names of. In asserting that the truth of a proposition depends on the conformity of import between its terms, as, for instance, that the proposition, Socrates is wise, is a true proposition, because Socrates and wise are names applicable to, or, as he expresses it, names of, the same person ; it is very remark- able that so powerful a thinker should not have asked himself the question, But how came they to be names of the same person ? Surely not because such was the intention of those who invented the words. When mankind fixed the meaning of the word wise, they were not thinking of Socrates, nor, when his parents gave him the name of Socrates, were they thinking of wisdom. The names huppen to fit the same person because of a certain fact, which fact was not known, nor in being, when the names were invented. If we want to know what the fact is, we shall find the clue to it in the connotation of the names. A bird or a stone, a man or a wise man, means simply an object having such and such attributes. The real meaning of the word man, is those attributes, and not Smith, Brown, and the remainder of the individuals. The word mortal, in like manner, con- notes a certain attribute or attri- butes ; and when we say, All men are mortal, the meaning of the proposi- tion is, that all beings which possess the one set of attributes possess also the other. If, in our experience, the attributes connoted by man are always accompanied by the attribute connoted by mortal, it will follow as a conse- quence, that the class man will be wholly included in the class mortal, and that mortal will be a name of all things of which man is a name : but why ? Those objects are brought under the name by possessing the attributes connoted by it : but their possession of the attributes is the real condition on which the truth of the proposition depends ; not their being called by the name. Connotative names do not precede, but follow, the attributes which they connote. If one attribute happens to be always found in conjunction with another attribute, the concrete names which answer to those attributes will of course be predicable of the same subjects, and may be said, in Hobbes' language, (in the propriety of which on this occasion I fully concur,) to be two names for the same things. But the possibility of a concurrent applica- tion of the two names, is a mere con- sequence of the conjunction between the two attributes, and was, in most cases, never thought of when the names were introduced and their signification fixed. That the diamond is combustible, was a proposition certainly not dreamt of when the words Diamond and Combustible first received their meaning ; and could not have been discovered by the most ingenious and refined analysis of the signification of those words. It was found out by a very different process, namely, by exerting the senses, and learning from them, that the attri- bute of combustibility existed in the diamonds upon which the experiment was tried ; the number or character of the experiments being such, that what was true of those individuals might be concluded to be true of all substances "called by the name," that is, of all substances possessing the attributes which the name con- notes. The assertion, therefore, when analysed, is, that wherever we find certain attributes, there will be found a certain other attribute : which is not a question of the signification of names, but of laws of nature ; the order existing among phenomena. NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. § 3. Although Hobbes' theory of Predication has not, in the terms in which he stated it, met with a very favourable reception from subsequent thinkers, a theory virtually identical with it, and not by any means so perspicuously expressed, may almost be said to have taken the rank of an established opinion. The most gener- ally received notion of Predication decidedly is that it consists in refer- ring something to a class, i.e., either placing an individual under a class, or placing one class under another class. Thus, the proposition, Man is mortal, asserts, according to this view of it, that the class man is in- cluded in the class mortal. "Plato is a philosopher," asserts that the individual Plato is one of those who compose the class philosophers. If the proposition is negative, then, instead of placing something in a class, it is said to exclude something from a class. Thus, if the following be the proposition. The elephant is not carnivorous ; what is asserted (according to this theory) is, that the elephant is excluded from the class carnivorous, or is not numbered among the things comprising that class. There is no real difference, except in language, between this theory of Pre- dication and the theory of Hobbes. For a class ia absolutely nothing but an indefinite number of individuals denoted by a general name. The name given to them in common, is what makes them a class. To refer anything to a class, therefore, is to look upon it as one of the things which are to be called by that common name. To exclude it from a class, is to say that the common name is not applicable to it. How widely these views of predi- cation have prevailed, is evident from this, that they are the basis of the celebrated dictum de omni et nvllo. When the syllogism is resolved, by all who treat of it, into an inference that what is true of a class is true of all things whatever that belong to the claes ; and when this is laid down by almost all professed logicians as the ultimate principle to which all reasoning owes its validity ; it is clear that in the general estimation of logicians, the propositions of which reasonings are composed can be the expression of nothing but the process of dividing things into classes, and referring everything to its proper This theory appears to me a signal example of a logical error very often committed in logic, that of Harepov trp&repov, or explaining a thing by something which presupposes it, When I say that snow is white, I may and ought to be thinking of snow as a class, because I am asserting a proposition as true of all snow : but I am certainly not thinking of white objects as a class ; I am thinking of no white object whatever except snow, but only of that, and of the sensation of white which it gives me. When, indeed. I have judged, or assented to the propositions, that snow is white, and that several other things are also white, I gradually begin to think of white objects as a class, including snow and those other things. But this is a conception which followed, not preceded, those judgments, and therefore cannot be given as an explanation of them Instead of explaining the effect by the cause, this doctrine explains the cause by the effect, and is, I conceive, founded on a latent misconception of the nature of classification. There is a sort of language very generally prevalent in these discus- sions, which seems to suppose that classification is an arrangement and grouping of definite and known indi- viduals : that when names were im- posed, mankind took into considera- tion all the individual objects in the imiverse, distributed them into parcels or lists, and gave to the objects of each list a common name, repeating this operation toties quoties until they had invented all the general names of which language consists ; which having been once done, if a question IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS. 6i ■ubsequently arises, whether a certain general name can be truly predicated of a certain particular object, we have only (as it were) to read the roll of the objects upon which that name was conferred, and see whether the object about which the question arises is to be found among them. The framers of language (it would seem to be supposed) have predetermined all the objects that are to compose each class, and we have only to refer to the record of an antecedent decision. So absurd a doctrine will be owned by nobody when thus nakedly stated ; but if the commonly received explana- tions of classification and naming do not imply this theory, it requires to be shown how they admit of being reconciled with any other. General names are not marks put upon definite objects ; classes are not made by drawing a line round a given number of assignable individuals. The objects which compose any given class are perpetually fluctuating. We may frame a class without knowing the individuals, or even any of the individuals, of which it may be com- posed ; we may do so while believing that no such individuals exist. If by the meaning of a general name are to be understood the things which it is the name of, no general name, except by accident, has a fixed meaning at all, or ever long retains the same meaning. The only mode in which any general name has a definite mean- ing, is by being a name of an indefinite variety of things ; namely, of all things, known or unknown, past, present, or future, which possess cer- tain definite attributes. When, by studpng not the meaning of words, but the phenomena of nature, we dis- cover that these attributes are pos- sessed by some object not previously known to possess them (as when chemists found that the diamond was combustible), we include this new object in the class ; but it did not already belong to the class. We place the individual in the class because the proposition is true ; the proposi- tion is not true because the object ia placed in the class.* It will appear hereafter, in treating of reasoning, how much the theory of that intellectual process has been vitiated by the influence of these erroneous notions, and by the habit which they exemplify of assimilating all the operations of the human under- standing which have truth for their object, to processes of mere classifi- cation and naming. Unfortunately, the minds which have been entangled in this net are precisely those which have escaped the other cardinal error commented upon in the beginning of the present chapter. Since the revo- lution which dislodged Aristotle from the schools, logicians may almost be divided into those who have looked upon reasoning as essentially an affair of Ideas, and those who have looked upon it as essentially an affair of Names. Although, however, Hobbes' theory of Predication, according to the well- known remark of Leibnitz, and the avowal of Hobbes himself,t renders * Professor Bain remarks, in qualifica- tion of the statement in the text (Logic, i. fO). tliat the word Class h;is two meanings ; "the class definite, and the class indefinite. The class definite is an enumeration of actual individuals, as the peers of the realm, the oceans of the globe, the known planets. . . . The class indefinite is un- emimerated. Such classes are stars, planets, gold-bearing rocks, men, poets, virtuous. . . . In this last acceptation of the word, class name and general name are identicaL The class name denotes an indefinite number of individuals, and connotes the points of community or likeness." The theory controverted in the text, tacitly supposes all classes to be definite. I have assumed them to be indefinite; because for the pixrposes of Logic, definite classes, as such, are almost useless ; though often serviceable as means of abiidged ex- pression. (Vide infra, book iii. ch. ii.) t " From hence also this may be de- duced, that the first truths were arbitrarily made by those that first of all imposed names upon things, or received them from the imposition of others. For it is true (for example) that man is a living creature, but it is for this reason, tnat it pleased men to impose both these names on the same thing."— Computation or Logic, ch. iii. sect. 8. 62 NAMES AND PROPOSITIONS. truth and falsity completely arbitrary, with no standard but the will of men, it must not be concluded that either Hobbes, or any of the other thinkers who have in the main agreed with him, did in fact consider the distinc- tion between truth and error as less real, or attached less importance to it, than other people. To suppose that they did so would argue total unac- quaintance with their other specula- tions. But this shows how little hold their doctrine possessed over their own minds. No person, at bottom, even imagined that there was nothing more in truth than propriety of ex- pression ; than using language in conformity to a previous convention. When the inquiry was brought down from generals to a particular case, it has always been acknowledged that there is a distinction between verbal and real questions ; that some false propositions are uttered from ignor- ance of the meaning of words, but that in others the source of the error is a misapprehension of things ; that a person who has not the use of language at all may form propositions mentally, and that they may be untrue, that is, he may believe as matters of fact what are not really so. This last admission cannot be made in stronger terms than it is by Hobbes himself,* though he will not allow such erroneous belief to be called falsity, but only error. And he has himself laid down, in other places, * "Men are subject to err not only in affirming and denying, but also in percep- tion, and in silent cogitation. . . . Tacit errors, or the errors of sense and cogita- tion, are made by passing from one imagi- nation to the imagination of another dif- ferent thing ; or by feigning that to be past, or future, which never was, nor ever shall be ; as when by seeing the image of the sun in water, we imagine tiie sun itself to be there ; or by seeing swords, that there has been, or shall be, fighting, be- cause it uses to be so for the most part ; or when from promises we feign the mind of the promiser to be such and such ; or, lastly, when from any sign we vainly imagine something to be signified which is not. And errors of this sort are com- mon to all things that have sense."— C