THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC AN INQUIRY INTO THE PRINCIPLES OF ACCURATE THOUGHT AND SCIENTIFIC METHOD P. COFFEY, PH.D. (LOUVAIN) PROFESSOR OF LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS, MAYNOOTH COLLEGE, IRELAND IN TWO VOLUMES VOL. II. METHOD, SCIENCE, AND CERTITUDE NEW YORK PETER SMITH 1938 FIRST PUBLISHED, 1912 REPRINTED 1938 BY SPECIAL ARRANGEMENT WITH LONGMANS, GREEN AND CO., LONDON FEB 1 6 1948 PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA CONTENTS OF VOLUME II. PART IV. METHOD : OR THE APPLICATION or LOGICAL PROCESSES TO THE CERTAIN ATTAINMENT OF TRUTH. CHAPTER I. GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD. PAGE 200. Transition to Part IV i 201. Logic and Method 2 202. Synthesis and Analysis 7 203. General Rules of Method 10 204. Didactics : Analysis and Synthesis in Teaching 14 205. Scholastic Methods of Exposition and Debate 16 CHAPTER II. INDUCTION IN ITS VARIOUS SENSES. INTRODUCTORY AND HISTORICAL NOTIONS. 206. The Problem of Induction : Ascent from the Particular to the Universal 23 207. The so-called " Inductive Syllogism " : or " Induction by Simple Enumeration of Instances" — "Complete" and "Incomplete" . 27 208. Scientific Induction as Treated by Aristotle and the Mediaeval Scholastics 32 209. Lord Bacon's Novum Organon : The Two Ideals of Generalization . . 37 210. Modern Conceptions of Induction : Newton, Whewell, J. S. Mill, Jevons 41 211. Analysis and Illustration of the Process of Scientific Induction . . 44 212. Scientific Induction and Deductive Inference 48 213. Relation of Antecedent to Consequent in Induction and in Deduction: The Latter Considered as an " Inverse Process " .... 53 CHAPTER III. PRESUPPOSITIONS OF INDUCTION : CONCEPTS OF " REASON " AND " CAUSE ". 214. Justification of Chapters III. and IV 56 ->I5. "Reality" and the " Principle of Sufficient Reason " .... 58 vi TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE 216. The "Principle of Causality" in Induction: Aristotle's Classification of Causes . . 61 217. "Purpose" or "Design": "Final Causes" and "Law" in Physical Nature 66 218. Contrast between Traditional and Empiricist Conceptions of Efficient Causality 70 219. The Sensist or Empiricist View of Causality : Mill's Teaching . . 75 220. Causality, Sequence in Time, and Contiguity in Space .... 80 221. "Plurality of Causes": "Reciprocal" and "Non-Reciprocal" Causal Relation 84 222. Science and the Discovery of " Causes " and " Laws " .... 86 CHAPTER IV. PRESUPPOSITIONS OF INDUCTION : UNIFORMITY OF NATURE. 223. Interpretations of the Principle of Uniformity in Nature 93 224. Ultimate Rational Grounds ot our Belief in Uniformity : The Scholastic, Empiricist, and Idealist Views 99 225. Relation of the Principle to Induction and to Deduction . . . .113 CHAPTER V. HYPOTHESIS: ITS NATURE, FUNCTIONS, AND SOURCES. 226. Functions of Scientific Hypothesis 120 227. Scientific Value of Various Kinds of Hypothesis 122 228. Nature and Verification of Causal or Explanatory Hypotheses . . 127 229. The R61e of Analogy in Verification : Ultimate Systematic Conceptions 135 230. Verification by Cumulative Evidence 141 231. " Postulates " and their Justification : " Truth " of Verified Hypotheses . 142 232. Theism as a Verifiable Hypothesis 145 233. Summary of Logical Requirements for a Legitimate Hypothesis . . 148 234. Sources of Scientific Hypotheses : Analogy ... . . 151 235. Worth of .Analogy : Its Function in Verification 155 236. The Argument from " Example " in Aristotle 158 237. "Analogy" as understood by Aristotle 160 CHAPTER VI. METHOD OF DISCOVERING CAUSAL LAWS BY ANALYSIS OF FACTS : OBSERVATION AND EXPERIMENT. 238. Observation and Selection : Initial Precautions 162 239. Experiment : its Relations to Observation 164 240. The Function of Experiment : Difficulties of Analysis .... 165 241. The "Rules" or "Canons" of Inductive Analysis; "Methods" of " Agreement " and " Difference " 172 242. Combination of " Agreement " and " Difference " 179 243. Method of " Concomitant Variations ". Measurement. Statistics. . 186 244. Method of" Residues," "Conjunction of Causes," and " Intermixture of Effects" 193 245. Scope of the " Methods " : Use of Symbols .... . 197 246. Quantitative Determination : Modes of Measurement . . . .201 247. " Empirical Laws " and their Explanation : Transition to Part V. . .205 TABLE OF CONTENTS vii PART V. THE ATTAINMENT OF SCIENCE AND CERTITUDE. CHAPTER I. SCIENCE AND DEMONSTRATION. PAGE 248. Elementary Notions Defined: Truth, Ignorance, Error, Evidence, Certitude, Opinion, Probability, Doubt 210 249. Three Kinds of Certitude ; Metaphysical, Physical, and Moral . . 214 250. Necessary Truth of Metaphysical Laws ; Contingent Truth of Physical Laws and Facts 217 251. Aristotle's Ideal of " Scientific " Knowledge 223 252. Nature and Conditions of Demonstration 225 253. Restricted Scope of Aristotelean " Science " 229 254. Principal Kinds of Proof 232 255. Demonstration and Scientific Explanation. " Popular Explanation " . 235 256. Limitations of Scientific Explanation 239 257. An Erroneous View of Explanation 241 258. Discovery and Proof of Truth by Induction and by Deduction . . . 243 259. Moral Certitude in the " Human " Sciences .... . 248 260. Belief on Authority 250 261. Historical Science and Certitude : Its Criteria and Sources . . . 253 CHAPTER II. OPINION AND PROBABILITY. 262. Nature of Probability : Cumulative Evidence : " Practical " Certitude . 260 263. Probable Arguments : The Aristotelean Enthymeme .... 263 264. Estimation of Probability : The Concept of " Chance " . . . .268 265. Conditions for the Mathematical Estimation of Probability . . . 272 266. Rules for Estimating Probability 276 267. Inverse Probability : Bernoulli's Theorem : Elimination of Chance . . 278 268. Application of the Calculus of Probability to Natural and Social Phenomena 282 269. Function of Statistics and Averages : Their Right and Wrong Interpre tations 285 CHAPTER III. ERROR AND FALLACIES. 270. Logical Treatment of Error and its Sources 294 271. Error and Fallacy 296 272. Some Attempted " Classifications " of Fallacies : " Formal " and " Material " Fallacies 298 273. Fallacies Incident to Conception 303 274. Fallacies Incident to Judgment and Immediate Inference . . . 308 275. Fallacies Incident to Method 315 QUESTIONS 338 GENERAL INDEX 343 PART IV. METHOD ; OR THE APPLICATION OF LOGICAL PRO CESSES TO THE ATTAINMENT OF TRUTH. CHAPTER I. GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD. 200. TRANSITION TO PART IV.— We have now completed our examination of the formal aspect of the reasoning process, and of the rules that guarantee its formal correctness or validity (Part III.). But the object of all reasoning, of all science and philosophy in fact, is to arrive at a certain knowledge of truth ; and, to secure this, it is not enough that our reasoning processes be correct or valid formally : the judgments involved in them must, furthermore, be all both true and certain. Truth is, as we saw (9, 79), contained in the mental act of judgment, to which the operations both of inference and of conception are thus subsidiary. An analysis of the material or " truth " aspect of inference will therefore, of necessity, direct our attention once more to the judgments of which our inferences are composed, and to the concepts or ideas which enter into our judgments (Parts I. and II.). After having separately examined each of the three mental operations, of conception, judgment, and inference, our next concern is to inquire how we reach true judgments, especially those true universal judgments which constitute scientific knowledge : how, in other words, we are to exercise those three mental operations on the data of knowledge to the best advantage for the acquiring of truth : how we are to regulate and co-ordinate those mental acts, conception, judgment, and reasoning, in exploring the various departments of the knowable universe. This portion of logical doctrine is variously described as applied logic, methodology, or the science of logical method. VOL. II. I 2 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC In all logical inference, our reason for assenting to the conclusion is its evident connexion with premisses to which we have already assented. But how do we come to assent to these latter ? Either because they are self-evident — like the universal axioms involved in all inference (193), — or derived by demonstrative evidence from such self-evident truths, or generalized by induction from observed facts. The general truths of the sciences may, then, be roughly divided into these three classes : (a) self-evident axioms or principles, such, for example, as " The whole is greater than its part " : these are reached by a comparatively simple process of intellectual abstraction and intuition, involving Definition and Division of concepts, and their mutual comparison in judgment ; (£) general truths that are not self-evident, but which have been generalized by Induction from observed facts ; (c) conclusions inferred by Demonstration from truths of classes (a) or (£). Before the inductive method was developed, attention was largely de voted, in the traditional Aristotelean logic, to definition, division, and demonstration — the tres modi sciendi as they were called.1 Definition, by analysing our concepts of things into the simplest possible notions, gives rise to certain primordial, self-evident relations between these notions. These relations are formulated in judgments and propositions which furnish the foundations of the scientific edifice— the principles of the sciences. While definition thus analyses our concepts, and gives us information about the nature of their objects, it thereby also shows us wherein those objects agree in thought and wherein they differ from one another. The process of differentiation, or classification, or division, is thus the indispensable con comitant of definition. According as the mind becomes equipped with its elementary ideas and judgments by means of sense observation, and intellectual abstraction and intuition, it has recourse to the third mode of procedure, demonstration : it draws certain and evident conclusions from self-evident principles, and from these conclusions still further conclusions, and so on. The employment of those various functions or factors of science, for the advance of knowledge, is what the Scholastics called METHOD. The process of (real) definition, understood in the Scholastic sense as an explanation of the nature of a thing, and the concomitant process of (real) division or classification, were always regarded in Aristotelean philosophy as material processes, involving observation and analysis of facts, abstraction, generalization, comparison, and even inference and verification of hypotheses — in a word, all the processes nowadays described as " subsidiary to in duction ". These made up the analytic stage of the Scholastic method, as demonstration constituted its synthetic stage. 20 1. LOGIC AND METHOD. — Before investigating the method 1Cf. ZIGLIARA, Logica, (13), (44). GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD 3 or methods of applying the mental processes we have been mentioning, to the pursuit of truth, it will be useful here to take a glance by anticipation at the main departments of human knowledge which the logician may have in mind, and from which he may draw his illustrations, in investigating such methods. We have pointed out already, in common with all logicians, that it is not the function of logic to explore the provinces of the special sciences in order to expound the various modes of procedure peculiar to each. This is the function of the special sciences themselves : each has, or ought to have, its own special methodology. Logic ought to confine itself to an exposition of those guiding laws and principles of reasoning and research which are so universal that the mind must conform to them always and in every department of rational investigation.1 In thus limiting its field, logic will not be aiding the study of the special sciences so directly as it will aid the study of philosophy proper ; for philosophy presupposes a general knowledge of all the special sciences and endeavours to synthesize their results ; and in this arduous work it is guided by no other " rules of philo sophizing" than the general canons and laws laid down in logic. Indeed, if there be any science to which logic should serve as a special introduction, it is philosophy, the " general science," and not any of the special sciences. But it is difficult to carry out in practice what is so simple in theory. Just because philosophy does take up, interpret, collate, and harmonize — as far as possible — the assumptions and conclu sions of all the special sciences — mathematical, physical, natural, anthropological, social, economical, ethical, etc. — it is not easy in practice to say where the work of each special science ceases and that of philosophy begins. And so it is, too, with regard to the scope of logic. This may easily deviate into the investigation of methodological details proper to special sciences ; or — which is a more serious mistake — it may, by losing sight of some depart ments of human experience and falling unduly under the influence of others, set forth, as general canons of philosophical investiga tion, methods that may be valid only within the narrower pre suppositions of some special science or group of sciences. These 1 " Logica tradit communem modum procedendi in omnibus aliis scientiis. Modus autem proprius singularum scientiarum, in scientiis singulis circa principium tradi solet."— ST. THOMAS, In II. Metaph. lect. 5. I * 4 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC are mistakes which writers on inductive logic since the time of Mill have not successfully avoided. Nor is it difficult to one looking back, to see why such mistakes were, humanly speaking, almost unavoidable. At different epochs men engaged in the investigation of those higher and deeper problems which lie along the confines of philo sophy and the special sciences, have been very differently impressed as to the relative values of these latter in advancing human know ledge. At one time the attention of scholars is drawn more exclusively to one group of sciences, and again to another group : and the logic of each period will be found to reflect faithfully the then prevailing attitude, by its fuller consideration of the methods and data of the dominating group. Thus we see that, broadly speaking, the Middle Ages wit nessed an exhaustive development of the logic of Deductive Reasoning. This was because men were then more satisfied with their principles of knowledge, and perhaps more religiously-minded ; because they set greater store on a knowledge of man's nature and destiny than on a knowledge of the external universe ; be cause for progress in the former they relied on (deductive) reason ing from great, broad, general principles and truths that were universally accepted at the time — some on the authority of God as being revealed by Him, others as self-evident, others again as sufficiently established partly by their intrinsic evidence and partly by the common assent and authority of the learned of past ages. Then came the period of the Renaissance, a period of doubt about hitherto received principles, of revolt against authority and rejection of traditional views and methods. On the one hand, the hitherto accepted teachings of philosophy and religion were critically re-examined ; and this new analysis had finally the effect of adding to the traditional logic an extensive discussion on the possibility and grounds of human certitude, and on the ultimate criteria or tests of truth (17). On the other hand, a closer attention to the study of external nature led to a wonder ful progress in the domain of the physical sciences. The cultiva tion of this fertile field of research has been rewarded by rich and useful discoveries ; the physical universe is being eagerly explored and made to yield up its secrets ; and the general laws and con ditions according to which its phenomena unroll themselves are the keys by which its most hidden agencies are brought to light and utilized by human enterprise. Hence the high degree of GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD 5 importance that has been attached to general truths of the physical order — in contrast with these other general truths that have to do with man's religion, natural or supernatural, with his moral conduct in life, with the inner nature of his own mind and soul, with the ultimate purpose of his existence, and with his final destiny.1 Hence, too, the very large and prominent place devoted in modern treatises on logic to an analysis of the method and processes by which general truths about the physical universe can be securely and certainly established : as if these were the only general truths of importance, or, anyhow, of most importance, to man ; as if physical induction were the only or the chief method of reaching a certain knowledge of the weightiest truths to which the human mind can hope to attain. The modern logician of induction invites us into chemical, physical and physiological laboratories ; he familiarizes us with test-tubes and balances, with boilers and engines and dynamos, with microscopes and telescopes ; he teaches us how to observe and experiment, how to detect analogies between physical phenomena, how to construct hypotheses foreshadowing the laws according to which these phenomena take place ; he lays down canons which will help us to simplify our data by elimination of the unessential, and so to test or establish — or, it may be, to reject or to modify — our hypotheses, until we thus finally discover and generalize some abstract law about the conditions requisite for the occurrence and the recurrence of some physical event. But the general truths we reach about the external universe, as distinct from man himself, by the application of such methods, constitute only one department of human knowledge— an important one, no doubt, yet by no means the most important. There is, for instance, the wide and fertile, if more difficult, department of human research which has for its object the phenomena of human activity in the individual, in the family, and in the State : the domains of anthropology and psychology, of the social, economic, and political sciences. The methods of discovering and establi shing general truths in these sciences should have no smaller degree of interest for the logician than the method of reaching, say, the law of universal gravitation. Yet the modern logician tells us comparatively little about the former : about statistics and averages and the canons of probability : the various means of reaching another class of general truths or laws which may have immense practical interest for us, even though we can have only moral, and not physical or metaphysical, certitude concerning them. And what about the innumerable truths, or supposed truths, some of which inform us of particular facts in human history, such as the conquest of Gaul by Caesar, or the crucifixion of Christ ; others of which embody generalizations such as that " Moral excellence in men and nations results from their posses sion of deep and true religious beliefs " ; and all of which are accepted and believed, by nine-tenths of those who do accept and believe them, on the authority of their fellowmen, on the strength of historical evidence? If the 1 C/. JOSEPH, op. cit., pp. 344, sqq. 6 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC logician thinks it a part of his duty to teach us how to measure masses and motions of matter by the " method of means," the " method of least squares," 1 etc., may we not reasonably expect from him an equally detailed code of directions in the task, let us say, of estimating the value of the historical evi dence for and against the alleged fact— so momentous in human history — that Christ rose from the dead after His crucifixion ? The logician is no more debarred from dealing with the methodology of " metaphysical," or "ethical," or "historical" truth, than he is from investi gating the methods of discovering and establishing " physical " truths. Truths and theories, facts and phenomena, whether real or alleged, whether "re ligious " or " scientific," forming, as they all do, the common data of philosophy, fall equally within the sphere of logic. They are all subjects of human investi gation : and it ought to be, therefore, the function of general logic, not to teach us how to explore the hidden recesses of any particular department, but rather to give us a general training in the method of discovering and proving truth : a training which will help us equally well all round, which will aid us in determining whether God exists and has spoken to us through Christ, no less than in determining whether radium cures cancer, or whether alleged " telepathic " phenomena are mere coincidences. The logician must, of course, ultimately use his own discretion in deter mining whether he ought in a general way to indicate the main methods in use in this or that special department of science ; and it is just here, in judging which departments are worthy of a more detailed attention, that he will be influenced, consciously or unconsciously, by the general trend of intellectual activity in his own time and country. In this way he is exposed to the danger of unduly emphasizing the scope and import of certain special methods of scientific research, or even of setting them up as the only methods of attain ing to scientific truth. Now, modern inductive logic shows pretty clear evidence of suffering from an undue bias of the sort just outlined : it has concerned itself somewhat too exclusively with the mathematically exact quantitative methods of the physical sciences, and it has thus fostered an unwholesome tendency to conceive and treat all human experience as amenable to the laws and methods of mechanics. It has been more or less obsessed by the rigid determinism of the "mechanical theory of the universe," which was so much in vogue about half a century ago. There is something one-sided in this tendency to cultivate the positive, physical sciences, on the lines of mechanically exact, quantitative laws, and to develop, in logic, a corresponding methodology of them — to the exclusion of the human sciences, the knowledge of man's nature, origin, and destiny, of his conduct and religion, of his social activity and its history. The intellectu ally cogent evidence of the "exact " sciences — mathematics, whether pure or applied to physics — lends itself, of course, most readily to clear, logical treatment. But the " exact " sciences are not the only sciences, nor is the assent which is given on intellectually cogent evidence the only assent that deserves to be called scientific. Assents that are freely given may be scientific and certain, provided that the evidence is as strong as can be reasonably ex pected in the matter under consideration. And even where these assents do fall 1 Cf. WELTON, Logic, ii., § 158; JOYCE, Logic, p. 368. GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD 7 short of certitude, the general method of weighing the evidence on which they are based forms the proper object of logic. It must be borne in mind that many of the processes to be hereafter de scribed as subsidiary to induction find their application very extensively outside the merely physical sciences, although they are for the most part illustrated by examples drawn from the domain of these latter.1 202. SYNTHESIS AND ANALYSIS. — Method (peOoSo^ means mode or manner of procedure, and may be defined as the proper arrangement of our mental processes in the discovery and proof of truth. If a truth needs proving, we cannot be said to have fully discovered it until we have proved or established it as a truth ; antecedently to this it is only a postulate or hypothesis. The method which thus leads to science is sometimes called inventive or constructive, to distinguish it from the method of teaching or expounding truths already established, this latter being known as didactic method (204). In scientific method it is customary to distinguish the influ ence of two great mental functions, analysis and synthesis ; and according to the predominance of either of these over the other in any department of scientific investigation, the latter is desig nated an analytic or a synthetic science. When a science sets out from a few simple ideas and a few necessary, universal principles, and proceeds to combine these elementary notions and relations, in order to deduce from them other new, less simple, more complex relations, its progress is synthetic (nrvv-riffii/ju). It goes from the simple to the complex, from the more general to the less general. It employs the method of composition, the synthetic method. Such a science is called a rational, deductive, abstract science. Pure mathematics, for example, sets out from a few neces sary and universal principles (" in materia necessaria "), with which the mind equips itself by the simple abstraction of a few element ary concepts from the data of sense, and by direct intellectual intuition of certain self-evident relations between those concepts. These relations it combines and multiplies successively, thus gradually forming definitions of the various thought-objects with which it deals, divisions of these objects into groups or classes, and demonstrations which show the relations, ever more and more complex, between these objects. It is thus ever and always discovering new abstract objects of thought, com- 1 C/. JOSEPH, Logic, pp. 472 sqq. 8 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC pounding, or building uf> its conceptions, so to speak, into more and more complex wholes, synthesizing its gradually acquired truths into a logical, harmonious, and progressive system. Throughout this whole work of elaboration, the student of the pure deductive sciences has no need to call in the aid of sense experience, of observation or experiment : he might conceivably become the greatest pure mathematician in the world without ever leaving his library. He would, of course, need charts or blackboards to aid his imagination in establishing the complex spatial or numerical relations he might desire to examine between the notions with which he deals. But it is from the primary notions, not from the figures or symbols before him, that he de duces even his remotest and most complex conclusions. If, however, it is true that such quiet seclusion and abstract speculation can produce a great mathematician, is it not equally true that they can never produce a great physical scientist ? A knowledge of the physical world implies actual, positive contact with Nature and its activities. The discovery of its laws is con ditioned by the observation of its concrete phenomena, and even by experimenting with these latter. It is the result of a long analytic process that has been called Induction : hence the designa tion, physical or positive or inductive sciences. When a science thus starts with concrete facts, with the data of observation and experiment, and aims at discovering general truths and formulating general laws, about those tacts, its progress is from the complex to the simple, from the particular to the general. This is the analytic method (ava\v(o) ; it finds its place mainly in the experimental sciences. We have already distinguished the reasoning by which we thus ascend to higher and wider laws, as regressive, in opposition to the progressive reasoning which is characteristic of the deductive sciences (187). Professor Welton * thus illustrates the distinction : " Instead of starting from an axiom of the widest generality, in physical science it more frequently happens that the highest and most general principles are the last to be discovered. ' Certain general propositions are first discovered (e.g. the laws of Kepler) under which the individual facts are syllogistically subsumed. The highest principles are discovered later (e.g. the Newtonian law of Gravitation) from which those general propositions are neces- 1 Logic, i., p. 392. GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD 9 sary deductions ' (Ueberweg, Logic, p. 465). . . . A demonstration of this kind is, therefore, called . . . Analytic". It is usual to draw a distinction between the two scientific methods : the synthetic, or that of the rational, deductive sciences ; and the analytic, or that of the experimental, inductive sciences. - There is reason for such a distinction : but only in this sense, that synthesis is the predominant feature of the former, and analysis of the latter ; not in the sense that either feature belongs exclusively to either group. No such separation of analysis from synthesis is possible in actual thought. As a matter of fact, the self-evident, a priori axioms of the rational sciences necessarily presuppose the mental analysis of some few elementary observations, by which the mind is equipped with the concepts that form those rational prin ciples. On the other hand, the general laws that are reached by the long and laborious analyses and inductions of the experimental scientist furnish us, in turn, with principles or starting points for synthetic or deductive reasoning processes. In reality, therefore, there is one and only one scientific method : the analytico-synthetic, or combined inductive and deductive method.1 Whether analysis or synthesis will predominate in any parti cular science, or at any particular stage in the growth of a science, will depend on whether the subject-matter is best approached from the side of the abstract universal, or of the concrete particular. But the two methods are not essentially opposed ; rather they "differ only as the road by which we ascend from a valley to a mountain does from that by which we descend from the mountain into the valley, which is no difference of road, but only a difference in the going".2 This, moreover, is what we should expect when we reflect on the unity of human nature ; and it is confirmed by the findings of psychology. Man derives his abstract ideas from data furnished by his senses. Sense observation must, therefore, be the forerunner of all rational speculation. The formation of abstract concepts from the data of sense experience involves analysis of the latter. These abstract concepts are in turn combined in manifold ways by the activity of the intellect, and are being constantly reapplied to the facts of sense observation. Thus it is that rational speculation is ever returning to those same sense realities which first awake its activity. All science is " of the uni versal and necessary " (to use the language of Aristotle) ; but it is no less true that all science must aim at explaining the contingent, individual facts of our sense experience. It must not only ascend by analysis and abstraction from the particular to the universal, from fact to law, from effect to cause, but it 1 C/. MELLONE, Introd. Text-Book of Logic, pp. 383 sqq. *Port Royal Logic, p. 314, quoted by Professor Welton, Logic, ii., p. 212. io THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC must also, by a regressive movement of thought, apply its abstract principles again to concrete facts, and by means of the former explain the latter. This combined and alternating use of analysis and synthesis will be more fully illustrated in connexion with the treatment of Induction, Demonstration, and Scientific Explanation. It is commonly employed in the physical sciences, and it is the only method by which a reliable philosophy of man and the universe can be constructed.1 There have been, in different ages, philosophers such as Descartes (1576-1650) and Spinoza (1632-1677), who have thought it possible to build up a philosophy by the purely synthetic or deductive method, on the basis of a few self-evident fundamental truths. Such projects are chimerical, for philosophy is expected to offer an intelligible interpretation of universal human experience, and must, therefore, set out from an analysis of this latter. The method of philosophy, too, like the methods of the sciences, is largely influenced by the prevailing general views and standpoints of each successive period : synthesis predominating in one school or in one epoch of philosophic development, analysis in another : the former, for instance, in Plato and Neo- Platonism, in St. Augustine and the early Middle Ages ; the latter in " scien tific " and " inductive " philosophy since the Renaissance ; and neither, perhaps, asserting undue supremacy in Aristotle, or in Scholasticism among its best accredited representatives, whether mediaeval or modern. A system of philosophy aims at working out and establishing some definite world-view, some interpretation of human experience as a whole. The method or methods that may be involved in the elaboration of such a thought-system will themselves usually imply assent to certain fundamental judgments, whether these be put forward as axioms or as postulates (203, 231). And hence it is that systems of philosophy are to be judged not only by their explicit positive teaching or contents, but also by their methods, for these too imply doctrines.'2 Indeed, it has been said that metaphysical systems differ merely in the stand points from which they approach the interpretation of experience. This is only an exaggeration of the undoubted truth that every such system is largely in fluenced and characterized by some predominating point of view. Thus, the idea of a process of Development, a tendency towards the realization of an ideal, as pervading not only thought but reality, has always exercised more or less influence on the trend of philosophical speculation. But the scientific discoveries of the last few centuries in regard to organic evolution among the forms of life, have led many to suspect the existence and operation of an all- pervading law of Evolution, and to adopt, in all departments, only methods of research directly based on this postulate. The wisdom of this procedure is questionable. If it is really unsound, results will in due time reveal its deficiencies. 203. GENERAL RULES OF METHOD. — Various rules or canons, of more or less practical utility, have been laid down for observance in the pursuit of truth, under the title of General Rules of Method. They are of the nature of counsels. A full 1 Cf. MERCIF.R, Logique, p. 374 : Pratique de 1'analyse et de la synth&se en philosophic. 2 Cf. DE WULF, Scholasticism Old and New, pp. 190-200. GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD u discussion of their grounds and significance would not be con venient at the present stage of our investigations. For the purpose of enumeration we may conveniently reduce them to the follow ing:— I. We should select as starting point the simplest, easiest, most familiar objects of thought. What is simplest and easiest to un derstand, will, however, depend on the amount and kind of knowledge already possessed by the seeker ; and will, therefore, be relative and variable. Each must determine, from his own know ledge, what element or elements of the particular subject-matter under investigation may be most easily grasped by him. Whether what is simplest in itself is simplest for us, will be largely determined by the nature of the subject-matter in hand. Looked at in itself, the abstract, universal principle or law is simpler, less complex in content, than any concrete fact under it : e.g. the law of gravitation than the fall of an apple ; * but it is not always this simple, abstract aspect of reality that comes first under our notice or is most familiar to us. Of some aspects of reality it is the widest and most general truths that are most easily grasped, as in the case of the axioms of the rational sciences ; and then the method employed will be mainly syn7 thetic. Oftener, however, it is the concrete, complex, many- sided fact of sense with which we are most familiar^ as in the data of the inductive sciences ; and then the method employed will be mainly analytic. II. We should proceed from the known to the unknown, GRADU ALLY, step by step, in an orderly, logical sequence of thought, and not hastily, irregularly, " PER SALTUM". To secure this, we must observe carefully all the canons of definition, division, reasoning, demonstration, etc. Failure in the observance of these canons will usually expose us to error, and will inevitably involve inversion, repetition, and consequent confusion. Innumerable examples of those defects have been instanced from the order followed in Euclid's elements of geometry.2 The importance of explicitly examining and test ing every step of our progress cannot be exaggerated. In no other way can thoroughly scientific knowledge be either secured or retained in the mind : whereas, on the other hand, a clearly perceived, logical, organic connexion between truth and truth is necessarily a powerful aid to memory. 1 WELTON, op. cit., p. 216. " ibid., p. 225. 12 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC Moreover, it is by careful separation of a problem or subject into its various parts and details that we are enabled to distin guish betweeen the accidental and the essential, and to avoid being misled by superficial resemblances and seeming connexions. Habit, association, familiarity, are apt to lead us astray. We very easily mistake invariable sequence for causality, and ap parent reasons for real ones.1 The principal sources and classes of such mistakes will be enumerated in the sections on Fallacies. III. While, on the one hand, we must never accept anything as true which we do not clearly know to be so, on the other hand, we must not expect the same degree of certitude, or the same cogency of evidence, in all the sciences. Disregard of the second portion of this rule has led many, especially in modern times, into scepticism, i.e. doubt about the capacity of the human mind to attain to certitude about anything. Taking too narrow a view of " science," they expect cogent evidence in the concrete subject-matter of the human sciences — social, economic, and ethical — evidence which, of their very nature, these sciences cannot be expected to yield.- And when it is not forthcoming they drift into scepticism. One would imagine that St. Thomas Aquinas was writing for the twentieth century, rather than the thirteenth, when he penned these sentences : " There are some who will not receive anything that is told them unless it is mathematically proved. This is usual with those who have had a mathematical training, because custom is second nature. But it may be also due to the possession of a strong imagination, combined with an undeveloped judicial faculty. Others there are who will not receive anything unless there is put before them some illustration of it that can strike their senses. This, too, results either from habit, or from the predominance of the influence exerted over them by their senses, or from want of intellectual discrimination. . . . Others, however, there are who 1 " An Englishman resident in some city in South America sees united in the inhabitants a profession of the Catholic religion, a great laxity of morals, and an absence of all energy, fortitude or perseverance. Neglecting our rule, he comes to the conclusion that there is a necessary connexion between Catholicism and the vices around him. . . . Or, again, we may have observed in the newspapers that a larger number of persons lose their lives by drowning on a Sunday than on any other day. On this fact the Scotch Presbyterian makes the remark that it can only be explained by the anger of God with all who take their pleasure on His Holy day : quite overlooking the circumstance that it is on Sunday that a great number ot excursionists of the middle and lower classes, who are unskilled in the use of boats and can rarely swim, take their pleasure on the water."— CLARKE, Logic, pp. 469, 470. 2 Cf. JOSEPH, Logic, p. 489. GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD 13 wish that everything offered them should be based on certitude, that is, as the fruit of diligent rational inquiry. This is the atti tude of a sound understanding in judging, and of sound reason in investigating : provided always that [such certitude] be not sought in matters where it cannot possibly be found" * IV. We must keep before us, as dearly as we can, the end to be attained in our inquiry or argument, and suit our method to the attainment of this end. Of course, when the end in view is the discovery of new knowledge, as distinct from the communication of knowledge already possessed, to others, we cannot have a clear or definite conception of what we are looking for : if we had, our inquiry would be superfluous. Still, we must have some general suspicion of it : otherwise we should not think of looking for it at all. Discoveries are, no doubt, sometimes made haphazard, by groping in the dark ; but this is the exception. As a rule, our progress in knowledge is guided by hypotheses, based on analogies with what we already know. Besides those general canons of method, special rules are sometimes formulated for the synthetic method, and special rules for the analytic. In the chapters dealing with Induction we shall examine the latter method at some length, and we shall there see that although the process by which we rise from the perception of concrete, individual facts of sense, to the apprehension of general truths, is one of very great importance, yet it is scarcely possible to formulate any mechanical set of guiding rules for it. It is the synthetic method that systematizes the truths discovered by analysis, and explains concrete reality by applying to the latter analytically dis covered laws. The rules laid down by some logicians for its employment are almost too obvious to need special statement. For instance, we are reminded that we must start either from axioms that are indisputably self-evident, or from general truths already proved. The usual error here is by defect, by taking for granted what is neither sufficiently simple to be self-evident, nor has been clearly proved — the fallacy known as Undue Assumption of Axioms. But philosophers, nowadays, not unfrequently err by excess, by demanding proof for what is so clearly self-evident as to be indemonstrable. They call into question the claim of any principles, however self-evident, to our uncon ditional intellectual assent. They doubt or deny that such abstract, self-evid ent axioms give us any insight into the real nature of things, confining the validity of such axioms to the sphere of subjective mental appearances, and according them at most a merely provisional acceptance as " assumptions " or " postulates " which may perhaps be some day verified as objectively valid, or may perhaps be destined to remain as mere " directive " or " regulative " principles of our thought-processes. It is, of course, a grave mistake thus to confound self-evident truths about the data of our ex perience with those mere " working hypotheses " and " methodological 1 Lect. V. in Metaph. 2. I4 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC assumptions " l which all investigators have sometimes to make, and which are perfectly legitimate in their proper sphere ; but an inquiry into the grounds of this erroneous tendency in modern philosophy would not be opportune here. Aristotle and the Scholastics examined in minute detail the requirements of the synthetic processes through which we advance by demonstrative rea soning from simple, self-evident first principles to more complex scientific conclusions. Their teaching will be outlined in the chapter on Demonstration. The remainder of the present chapter will be devoted to the application of analysis and synthesis to the teaching or exposition, as distinct from the discovery and proof, of truth. 204. DIDACTICS: ANALYSIS AND SYNTHESIS IN TEACHING.— When our object is not to discover truth as yet unknown to us, but to communicate what we know already to others, our method will be no longer constructive or inventive, but instructive or educative ; instructive if it aims merely at the communication of knowledge to the intellect ; educative if it aims at the formation of right mental habits and character as well. The latter is the scope of the art of Pedagogics ; the former alone, that of Didactics. This latter, therefore, is the sole concern of the logician. What, then, is the proper method of teaching or exposition ? Broadly- speaking, it is laid down that while the analytic method is the great method of discovery the synthetic method is the great method of instruction. And in general terms this is correct. But the statement needs to be carefully limited and qualified. The analytic method is not exclusively the method of discovery ; as witness the many discoveries of pure and applied mathematics. Nor, similarly, is the synthetic method always the best method of exposition. It is, of course, obviously the best in teaching the pure deductive sciences ; for in these the abstract principles, being simpler than their complex applications and conclusions, are more easily grasped by the beginner. But even here we need initial observation of concrete facts or instances as an aid to the abstrac tion of the simple notions, and to the intuition of the principles from which these sciences start. This initial stage is analytic in its character. The teacher familiarizes his pupils with concrete instances, facts, models, embodying the abstract principles he wishes them to grasp. In dealing with children especially, it is necessary to dwell at length on concrete things : these are more familiar : and the child's power of grasping even the simplest abstract principles, and reasoning from them, is comparatively undeveloped. The aim, at this early stage, will rather be to awaken the child's powers of obser vation and intuition, to arouse its curiosity and stimulate its interest by pre senting to it simple but attractive facts, combined with judicious interrogations and suggestions, calculated to draw out the pupil's powers of observation, comparison, and inference.2 1 Cf. JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 523. Cf. infra, 237. 2 Professor Willmann, in Germany, has published, under the title of Didaktik als Bildungslehre, a work of the highest merit on intellectual training. Habrich, a pupil of Willmann's, has supplied the teachers of intermediate education in Germany with a useful treatise on psychology, " Paedagogische Psychologic" in harmony with the principles of scholastic teaching. From another standpoint, cf. Herbert Spencer's works on Education. GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD 15 Moreover, the pupil should be trained, as far as possible, to discover, himself, the reasons and causes of the things observed by him. This involves the use of the analytic method, and develops the spirit of analysis in the learner. Such initiation into the method of independent personal investigation constitutes the immense difference there is between intellectual education proper and mere instruction. This method of teaching by suggestion, of drawing out the learner's powers by judicious questioning, is called the Socratic method, after the Grecian sage who made such a fruitful use of it. He, himself, appropriately called it the /iaievruoj Tt^vij, the art of intellectual obstetrics or mental mid wifery '.* This stage of analysis and observation is a necessary step towards ab straction of ideas and intuition of first principles. These notions and principles become in turn the explanatory reasons of the facts in which they are realized. The learner will next be taught, by an application of the synthetic method, to make use of those principles and laws for the under standing and explanation of concrete phenomena. Thus he will be taught to make use both of observation and of abstraction, both of analysis and of synthesis. The former without the latter would lead to narrowness of view, to the shortsighted philosophy of Positivism ; the latter without the former, to barren, empty speculations, and to the substitution of mere verbal explanation for real science. The sciences of observation develop the spirit of specialized research ; the mathematical and metaphysical sciences, the deductive, speculative turn of mind. It will be seen, therefore, that as a rule the method employed in exposition is the same as that employed in discovery ; that the art of teaching must follow nature ; that the mind of the learner must follow substantially the same path, whether he discover truth on his own account or be guided into the knowledge of it by one who is already in possession of it. Of course, when the exposition " is intended for well-prepared adults — as when one writes a text-book, the most appropriate method is, generally speaking, that of synthesis, as by that method the necessary relations of the parts of the subject to each other are most clearly shown." 2 But even here it is well to remember that the abstract, universal principle or law is not always the easiest to grasp at the starting-point. In an example from chemistry, given by Father Clarke in his Logic? we are told that "in each of these opposite processes [analysis and synthesis], the rule ... of commencing with what is more familiar, and thence proceeding to what is more remote and ] Socrates used to seek from others the knowledge they imagined they possessed, and which he himself pretended not to possess. His arguments took the form of dialogues, each in two parts. In the first, his " irony " confounded his interlocutor and convinced the latter of the weaknesses and drawbacks of his position. In the second, Socrates gradually drew from him a new and truer definition, a better under standing, of the matter in dispute. After silencing his opponent in the first or de structive stage of his discourse, he would begin by another series of questions to construct a new solution- of the problem — to substitute for the exploded error, or "spurious offspring," the " veritable fruit " of a " new-born " truth. The conclu sion of the dialogue thus became the " fruit of their personal reflection," the " child of their thought ".— C. PIAT, Socrate, pp. 106-109, Paris, Alcan, 1900. 8 WELTON, Logic, ii., p. 214. app. 471-74. 1 6 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC unfamiliar, is observed by the chemist. In his investigation he commences with that which is most familiar to ordinary mortals (nobis notiora), the water of the spring where thousands have drunk or bathed, and thence proceeds to the various chemical agents it contains which are to us a mystery, though in themselves they may be so simple as to admit of no further analysis. In im parting to others the results of his experiments he begins from what is simpler in itself and therefore more familiar to nature (naturae notiora), and thence proceeds to the complex results with which ordinary men are familiar, however complex they may in themselves be." But, if the audience is composed of " ordinary mortals " to whom the elements — however much simpler and more knowable they may be in themselves — are so many " mysteries," would not the lecturer be better advised to commence his exposition with the more familiar water, and to lead his audience along substantially the same path as he himself had followed in the first instance ? It seems rather a mistake, therefore, to apply the synthetic method exclusively, to the exposition of the subject-matter of those sciences in which analysis has been the main instrument of discovery. It is rightly used in the teaching of the pure deductive sciences such as mathematics ; but the exposition— at least the early stages of the exposition — of those sciences in which analysis, observation, and experiment have played a conspicuous part, should be rather analytic than synthetic. For example, the method followed by Maher and Mercier in their well-known treatises on psychology — the analytic or empirical phase leading up to the synthetic or rational one — is very much superior to the exclusively synthetic method adopted by many Scholastic writers in their Latin treatises on the subject. In accordance with the Scholastic axiom, Operari sequitur Esse, we ought to commence by examining and analysing the data on which our scientific knowledge of man is based, -viz, his activities, to arrive next at a knowledge of his faculties, and ultimately of his nature, origin, and destiny. We are only following nature in adopting such a course of analytico- synthetic exposition. The manner of using analysis in teaching will, however, be slightly different from the manner of using it in discovery.1 In the process of discovery, our analysis is necessarily slow, tedious, tentative, guided merely by analogy and hypothesis, often erratic owing to our being misled by false analogies and wrong hypotheses ; our experiments are necessarily multi plied and often practically blind, though seldom quite aimless. But in the process of exposition it is manifest that, having traversed the way before, and being now in possession of the scientific knowledge which was our goal, our didactic analysis may be much more direct and definite. We may exclude all the gropings and deviations that occurred in the first search after the truth, the misleading analogies and wrong hypotheses ; we may carefully select the most appropriate instances and experiments for disclosing the law in question to our pupils, and thus shorten the road for them : but we shall be travelling substantially the same road and employing the same method as previously. 205. SCHOLASTIC METHODS OF EXPOSITION AND DEBATE. The mediaeval Schoolmen followed the advice of the founder of the Lyceum : " Before you try to solve any problem," wrote Aristotle, " set forth clearly the reasons or difficulties that militate against the solution you are about to propose. In that 1 Cf. WELTON, ii., p. 220. GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD 17 way you will see better where is the heart or kernel of the question, the exact point in dispute ; you will fix your attention on it, and you will retain a firmer conviction of what you have seen to stand successfully the shock of the de bate." l Open the Summa Theologica of St. Thomas, that monumental synthesis of mediaeval wisdom " ad eruditionem incipientium" ." At the beginning of each Question (Quaestio) or Sub-question (Articulus] will be found a resume" of all the arguments, from reason and authority, that can be brought against the intended solution. They are introduced by the familiar " Videtur quod non . . . >}. Next comes the doctrinal affirmation of the thesis or solution, introduced by the words " Sed contra . . .," and usually illustrated rather than proved by some quotation from Scripture or from the Fathers. Then comes the body of the article (Corpus Articuli), introduced by the phrase " Respondeo dicendum quod . . ., " and containing the principle on which the solution is based, together with its main proofs in the usual syllogistic form. Finally, we have the further application of this same principle to the solution of each of the various difficulties proposed against the thesis at the commence ment : " Ad primum dicendum quod . . . " " Ad secundum . . . ," etc. At the public debates that were held in the mediaeval universities at certain fixed intervals during the year, usually before Christmas and Easter ("Zto- putationes Quodlibetales" as they were called), the procedure was slightly different. Any auditor might raise a question and indicate in a general way the arguments in favour of the solution that had his preference. The " re- spondens" i.e. the candidate for degrees, or his master, formulated their view, and based it on some fundamental argument. This position was at once attacked by the objector, and so the debate was opened. On the morrow, or one of the following days, the master repeated, arranged, and " determined," or settled definitively, the various questions discussed. These " Determina- tiones " have come down to us in the copious volumes of mediaeval philosophy and theology known as " Quodlibeta ".:i The method of carrying on academic debates in Scholastic philosophy and theology, still in use in schools, colleges, and universities, where these subjects are taught, is the same in principle as the above, if somewhat different in de tail. The exercise is strictly syllogistic, and it undoubtedly gives the student 1 Metaphysics iii., i ; Nicomachaean Ethics, vii., i. Here is the comment of St. Thomas : " Postis his quae videntur probabilia circa praedicta, prius inducamus dubitationes, et sic ostendemus omnia quae sunt maxime probabilia circa praedicta . . . quia si in materia aliqua dissolvantur difficultates et relinquuntur ut vera ilia quae sunt probabilia, sufficienter est determinatum." — loc. cit., lect. i. 2 " Quia catholicae veritatis doctor non solum provectos debet instruere, sed ad eum pertinet etiam incipientes erudire, propositum nostrae intentionis in hoc opere est ea quae ad Christianam religionem pertinent, eo modo tradere, secundum quod congruit ad eruditionem incipientium." A few brief sentences next tell us why he undertook the work : to rid theology of many useless questions, and to give an orderly exposition of it for the benefit ol learners; and in what spirit: "cum confidentia divini auxilii." Those few simple sentences form the whole preface or prologue to one of the greatest works that human genius has ever produced. 3 Cf. DE WULF, History of Medieval Philosophy, p. 258, note from Mandonnet's Siger de Brabant, etc. VOL. II. 2 1 8 THE SCIENCE Of LOGIC an invaluable training in exact reasoning. The following outline may be found helpful to academic disputants. The professor fixes upon a thesis, appoints a pupil to " defend " it, and one or more others to " object " to it. At the appointed time the defender (" defendens" " respondens ") enters the pulpit or bema, announces the thesis, adding, if desirable, a very brief exposition and proof. The objector (" ob- jiciens ") then asserts the contradictory of the thesis, proving his assertion by a syllogism. The defender resumes with the introductory phrase, " Sic argu- mentaris, Domine " (" This is your argument, Sir "), repeats the syllogism slowly and clearly, deliberating on the way in which he ought to deal with each premiss, the consequence, and the conclusion. Having repeated the syllogism, and also the introductory phrase, he again takes up and repeats once more the major, and now passes judgment on it : "I grant the major " (" Concedo majorem "), if he considers it true ; " I distinguish the major " (" Distinguo majorem "), if he sees in it a true sense and a false sense, which two he will separate by the addition of some well-chosen technical phrase to show the true sense and the false one, qualifying the false by " I deny " ("Nego"), and the true by "I grant" (" Concedo ") ; "Please prove the major " (" Faveas probare majorem "), if he considers the major entirely false ; " Let the major pass " (" Transeat major "), if he considers it irrelevant, or does not wish to pass definite judgment on it. In general, the objector should so construct his syllogisms that the major will not admit of total denial. Should the defender thus request his adversary to prove the major, the former need not proceed to the minor of the original syllogism, but listen to and deal with the proof brought forward for the major. If the defender has granted, or " distinguished " the major, he proceeds to repeat the minor, and either " denies " or " centra-distinguishes " it (" Nego minorem " or " Contra-dis- tinguo minorem "). It is only when he " denies " either premiss, or " distin guishes " .one and " contra-distinguishes " the other, that he has a right to " deny " the " consequence " or probative force (consequentia\ and therefore also the conclusion (consequens), of the syllogism ("Nego consequens et consequentiam "). To " centra-distinguish " the minor is to introduce the same distinction into it as into the major, granting the member correspond ing to that denied, and denying the member corresponding to that admitted, in the case of the major. It may sometimes be necessary to introduce a further distinction into either or both members of a distinction in order to sift fully the true from the false : this process is called " subdistinguishing " (" Subdistinguo "). The objector then continues the debate by proceeding to prove syllogis- tically the proposition denied by the defender, in the sense in which it was denied, commencing by the words, " I prove the major (or minor) denied " [" Probo majorem (or minorem} negatam "] ; and the defender proceeds to deal with the new syllogism as before. The objector may, at any stage, request or allow the defender to explain the precise force of the distinctions he has made in an answer : which the defender does as briefly and clearly as possible, introducing his explanation by the words, " I explain the distinction (distinctions) introduced " [" Et explico distinctionem datam (distinctiones datas) "]. Various courses may here present themselves to the objector. GENERAL OUTLINE OF METHOD 19 He may, notwithstanding the explanations offered, urge some proposition in the sense in which it has been denied. " But . . . Therefore the difficulty remains ". " Atqui . . . Ergo stat difficultas "). To which the defender replies, " I deny what you subsume " [" Nego subsumtum "]. The objector must then proceed to prove the proposition in the sense in which it has been denied. [" Probo subsumptum"~\ Or, again, the objector may urge the difficulty in a modified way, owing to some concessions made by the defender in his explanation ; which he does by commencing, " But I insist . . .," or, " But I urge the difficulty from your own admissions " (" Atqui insto . . .," or, " Atqui ex concessis urgeo difficultatem ". ) The real point of the difficulty ought to be kept in the minors as far as possible : the distinctions made ought to be real, not merely verbal, i.e. ex pressive of the same syllogism in different terms : quibbling and sophisms ought to be rigorously excluded : the questions selected ought to be the more serious ones, and the difficulties likewise : if the objector really feels the difficulty he is putting, so much the better ; waste of time, vain display of acuteness in making distinctions, or syllogisms more subtle than solid, should not be tolerated : the number of syllogistic steps leading up to the full solution of any difficulty will, of course, depend on the nature of the latter, but need not usually exceed four or five, unless, indeed, a modified phase of the difficulty, or a practically new difficulty, arises in the course of its solu tion : exactness, lucidity, brevity in the formation of syllogisms and distinctions, ought to be insisted on : and therefore, also, the necessary means to this end, viz. familiarity with the technical tertninology of the philosophical problems under discussion, and of philosophical terminology in general. Such are the principal canons laid down for observance in those exercises.1 There is no reason why they should not be conducted in the vernacular if necessary, rather than in Latin. The method is not wedded to any language ; and philosophical thinking would be much less erratic and illogical than it is at the present day if such disciplines formed an essential part of philosophical training. The Scholastic system of philosophy is identified with constructive and didactic methods which are nowadays eliciting a more accurate and sympa thetic appreciation from scholars, after a long period of prejudice and mis understanding. It took shape in the early mediaeval schools of Europe under the combined influence of St. Augustine, Plato, and a few of the logical writings of Aristotle. But the introduction of the latter's works into the Western schools towards the close of the twelfth century gave Scholasticism its predominantly Aristotelean character in the thirteenth.2 To its preponder ating use of synthesis as a constructive method we have already referred (201). Its elaborate system of teaching, too, has had a profound influence on the development of learning during many centuries. While recognizing its limitations, we are bound in the interests of historical truth to give it credit for many excellences. In general, we may say that the Scholastic method, 1 C/. ZIGLIARA, Logica, (46), De methodo disputandi. 2C/. DE WULF, History of Medieval Philosophy, pp. 101-48; Scholasticism Old and New, pp. 19-88, 168-82. 20 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC whether constructive or didactic, trains the mind to careful reflection and develops the critical faculty. In the first place, it certainly gives one the habit of disentangling and clearing up his ideas, of arranging them in order, of introducing rigorous logical sequence among them. Then, secondly, it teaches us to distinguish certainty from probability, truth from appearances, science from plausible theorizing, and established conclusions from unverified hypotheses. Thirdly, it inculcates a spirit of disinterested inquiry after the truth. In Scholastic philosophy truth is regarded in its native, unadorned beauty, so to speak ; it is sought for its own sake, and with a dispassionate calm : to the Scholastic, rhetoric makes no appeal : mere rhetoric excites the imagination and emotions, disturbs the balance of judgment, begets confusion of ideas, and hasty, ill-considered views. An inflammatory discourse that will arouse an untrained audience to the highest pitch of passion or enthusiasm may not be able to stand the test of a cold analysis, or the logic of the syllogism. The language of Scholasticism is the very antithesis of rhetorical. It " simply and solely expresses the intellectual concept, abstracting from all its relations to the other faculties of the soul, and from the reactions it may call forth in them. All possible obstacles between the mind and the objective truth are pitilessly set aside. Its style, stripped of all ornament, free from all feeling and senti ment and all the artifices of rhetoric, and hence so often accused of crudeness and barbarism, has all the exactness and precision of a mathematical formula or proposition ; it is pre-eminently truthful and clear. It was methodically and most successfully shaped into the aptest possible instrument for the systematization of thought : the instrument that was to build up the great Summae, whose materials lay scattered for generations through a whole world of literature. Reduced to the simple form and proportions of proposi tion and syllogism, those truths could be logically moulded into an organic whole in which each part received a prominence due to its relative import ance." 1 We are often nowadays reminded of what Plato said : We ought to tend to the truth with our whole soul — avv 6X17 rfj faxd • • • «»f TO Sv o8o third figure, but it is no more a true syllogistic process than is the apparent syllogism whose premisses contain no true universal, but only collective propositions. In fact it is just the reverse of the process which John Stuart Mill erroneously put forward as the true type of syllogistic reasoning (195). To observe successively that each of the planets describes an elliptical orbit around the sun, and then to say that all the planets describe such an ellipse, is simply to group together isolated observations in a formula to aid the memory, but this is not ascending from the particular to the universal. Similarly, to conclude that, because the senses a, b, c, d, e, are each an occasion of error, therefore all the senses are an occasion of error, is certainly not to go through a scientific reasoning process : but rather through an arithmetical process which simply tells us that five times one are five. Examples might be multiplied indefinitely. They all point to the same conclusion : that observation pure and simple puts us in possession of par ticular facts, and that the grouping together of those facts in a collective notion may help the memory and abbreviate the expression of thought, but will not lead to scientific knowledge of any necessary truth or law. Aristotle distinguished clearly between the formation of an actual whole from its parts and the elaboration of a universal notion ; " Even if we succeeded in showing separately," he writes,2 "whether by the same or by separate proofs, that equilateral, isosceles, and scalene triangles have each their in terior angles equal to two right angles, we should not yet have any right to assert the universal proposition ; ' The triangle, as such, has its interior angles equal to two right angles'." The separate proofs would not neces sarily have given us a universal knowledge ((cafldAov) of the triangle as such. Hence, we should not yet know whether the attribute, " having their interior 1 'H \t.\v bnarriW «ta0<$A.ov /coi 5i' ivayicalw.— ARISTOTLE, Post. Anal., i., 33. * Post. Anal., i.t 5(5-7). INDUCTION IN ITS VARIOUS SENSES 31 angles equal to two right angles" belonged to the triangle as such, and, therefore, to all possible triangles. Nor, even when we see that the three species, equilateral, isosceles, and scalene, are exhaustive of the genus triangle, can we be said to know scien tifically that the latter as such has the sum of its interior angles equal to two right angles : unless we have proved this attribute to belong to each of the three species, not on different grounds peculiar to each case, but on some common ground inherent in their common nature as triangles : " f i ravrov rfv rptywi/o) tlvcu. KOI IcroirXtvptf rj e»cdcm» rj iracriv — si eadem sit row esse ratio tn- angulo et aequilatero, aut cuique trianguli speciei aut omnibus."1 In order that such a conclusion be anything more than an enumerative judgment " it would be necessary to show that the reason for the inherence of P is the same in regard to all the parts of J/".2 But mere enumeration of the individuals of species (or of the species of a genus) cannot of itself reveal to us anything in their common nature to serve as a sufficient and necessary ground for predicating any attributes found in all the examined individuals (or species), about the species (or genus) as such. That Aristotle was acquainted with the true method of arriv ing at such a scientific or necessary knowledge of the nature of things we shall presently show (208). That he realized the in ability of an incomplete enumeration as such to prove a really general principle, is manifest from what he says of the so-called " inductive syllogism " described above. When he speaks of it as a way of "proving the major term of the middle by means of the minor"3 i.e. of proving the universal principle " M is P" 11 If anything is M it is P" which stands as major in the demon strative syllogism in the first figure, he does not mean "proving" in the strict sense of demonstration (aVoSet^t?), for strict demon stration is always by syllogisms in the first figure. He only means that the inductive syllogism is a way of illustrating, making clearer by instances or examples (BrjXouv ; TriOavvTepov, eaT€- 1 ibid., (6). 2 JOYCE, Logic, p. 229. The author observes that Euclid is usually able to do this in cases where he proves successively that something is true of each of all the possible instances of a logical whole. Cf. JOSEPH (op. cit., p. 503) : " The peculiar nature of our subject-matter [here] enables us to see that no other alternatives are possible within the genus than those which we have considered ; and therefore we can be sure that our induction is ' perfect '. The nature of our subject-matter further assures us that it can be by no accident that every species of the genus exhibits the same property ; and therefore our conclusion is a genuinely universal judgment about the genus, and not a mere enumerative judgment about its species. We are sure that a general ground exists, although we have not found a proof by it." No doubt, if we are assured that the species exhibit the same property, "by no accident," our conclusion is universal ; but, even then, we only know that it is so, not why it is so : until we can " show that the reason for the " property " is the same in regard to all " triangles. " Anal. Prior, ii., 23, (25). 32 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC pov, TToieiv},1 the general principle. " It is a mode of arranging a deductive argument so as to enable us to realize psychologically, the truth of the general principle (apx^i) which is the real major premise — a mode of illustrating the principle by bringing forward instances. Of course we cannot get ' all ' the instances, except where the number is limited ; but this fact does not vitiate an illustrative ' induction ' such as Aristotle had in view (cf. Anal, Post,!., 4, 73<*33)-"2 If, therefore, Aristotle regarded the conclusion of any enumer- ative induction as a strict, generic universal, he regarded the knowledge of this as reached not by enumeration, but by analysis.3 As long as we have any doubt about the completeness of our enumeration — which is nearly always, — and still rely on it alone for our conclusion, we can only have provisional and probable, not absolute and certain, knowledge, of the truth of the latter as a really general proposition. But both the process and the conclusion have in such cases this amount of utility, that they suggest to us, more or less forcibly, the existence of some natural law, i.e. some necessary natural connexion between the attribute predicated and the class of things in question. When we find that a, b, c, d, e, are P ; and know already that a, b, c, d, e, are 6" (whether all S or only some S, does not matter much), the surmise inevitably suggests itself that there may be something (say M~) in the nature of S (and therefore in all S's, whether examined or not) which is the natural ground for P. In other words, the conclusion ''Every S may, in virtue of the M that is in it, be P" suggests it self as an hypothesis worthy of investigation. Thus, our attention is drawn away from the number of S's ; and the tendency asserts itself not to aim at completing the enumeration — which is usually impossible, — but to examine the nature of the phenomena in ques tion, (the S's], and to seek in them for some natural attribute or pro perty (M} that will be the ground or reason for our predicating P of them. This marks the passage to scientific induction, whereby we are able, without a complete enumeration of instances, to rise from particular facts to the conception and discovery of some universal natural law. 208. SCIENTIFIC INDUCTION AS TREATED BY ARISTOTLE AND THE MEDIAEVAL SCHOLASTICS. — We have seen that the general conclusion, when derived from an incomplete enumeration 1 Cf. Anal. Prior, ii., 23 ; Top., i., 12 ; Anal. Post, i., 31. 3 MELLONE, op. cit., p. 247. 3 Cf. JOSEPH, Logic, pp. 356-57. INDUCTION IN ITS VARIOUS SENSES 33 of instances, is never certain, and that such induction is called "imperfect". We find it sometimes stated by modern logicians that the only way of ascending from the particular to the general, explicitly treated by Aristotle, and the only way known to the mediaeval Scholastic logicians, was that of enumerative induction, "complete " and " incomplete " ; that we find in these authors no trace of the method of modern scientific induction, the method of attaining to the universal by analysing a limited number of in stances and seeking therein a connexion of content, of attributes, a causal connexion, in the nature of the phenomena considered. Thus, Professor Welton writes : * " The scholastic logicians . . . made the essence of induction to consist in enumeration " ; and Dr. Mellone : 2 " With the mediaeval logicians induction became simply a process of counting particular things ". And these authors merely give expression to a traditional misconception, the origin and growth of which are clearly and succinctly accounted for by Father Joyce, in his Logic (p. 233): " The error seems to have arisen from the fact that the most famous of the Scholastics (St. Thomas, Albert the Great, Scotus) do not employ the term induction as the distinctive name of the inference by which we establish uni versal laws of nature. Following the terminology of Aristotle . . . they called it proof from experience (e'^Treip/o, experimentum, experientia). The signi ficance of the term induction was somewhat vague. It covered all argument from the particular to the general \cf. 206]. Hence (as e.g. in Scotus, Anal. Prior., ii., q. 8) it might include this meaning among others. But it was more usually employed to denote the formal process of perfect induction [207] arranged as an inductive syllogism. Moreover, it was sometimes pointed out, that our argument might be thrown into the form of an inductive syllogism : for, though the enumeration was incomplete, yet in these few instances we have equivalently seen all \cf. infra, 209]. It was by a later generation that the term induction was restricted to its present signification. Incautious readers, finding in certain passages the inductive syllogism described as the formula of inductive argument, jumped too hastily to the conclusion that the mediaeval philosophers rested their knowledge of the laws of nature on no basis but enumeration." Now, from the very fact that Aristotle and the Scholastics considered it possible to reach a truth about "#//," actual and possible, known and unknown, by an acquaintance with "some," they must have recognized a method of ascent to the " all" other than enumeration. And so they did : viz. the method nowadays known as Physical or Scientific Induction. When, therefore, we hear it stated that Scientific Induction is 1 op. dt., p. 33. ao/>. dt., p. 247. VOL. II. 3 34 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC an achievement of the modern mind, we must not infer that it was entirely unknown to the ancients. That to modern thought the honour was reserved of seizing upon the full significance of the method, and of applying it with such marked success, even the most ardent defenders of Aristotle and the Scholastics need not deny.1 But that the principle of this method was known to the latter, their works give unmistakable evidence. And, firstly, let us turn to Aristotle himself: — "Repeated sensations," he writes, "leave impressions in the memory, and these engender experience (tpnfipia) ; experience suggests abstraction, which separates from the particular instances the one in relation with the many (TO iv napa ra TroXXa), that is to say, the universal. But the abstract put in relation with an indefinite number of individuals, is a principle of science and of art".2 Turning, now, to St. Thomas's full and lucid commentary 3 on the passage just quoted, it would be difficult to find a plainer illustration of the modern inductive Method of Agreement : A physician has learned by repeated experiences that a certain herb has cured several patients of fever. From these experiences he ascends to the apprehension of the universal principle that " this kind of herb cures patients afflicted with this kind of fever". St. Thomas does not explicitly state the principle, or examine the process by which the ascent is made ; obviously, however, it is not made by enumeration of instances, complete or incomplete. 1 Ueberweg rightly remarks that " The recognition of the full significance of the inductive method in the sciences was reserved for modern times " (System der Logik, § 127). 3 Post. Anal., ii., 19, (5). 3 " Ex memoria multoties facta circa eamdem rem in diversis tamen singulari- bus, fit experimentum : quia experimentum [^uirtipfa] nihil aliud videtur, quam accipere aliquid ex multis in memoria retentis. Sed, tamen, experimentum indiget aliqua ratiocinatione circa particularia, per quam confertur unum ad aliud, quod est pro- prium rationis. Puta, cum talis recordatur quod talis herba multoties sanavit multos a febre, dicitur esse experimentum quod talis herba sit sanativa febris. Ratio autem non sistit in experimento particularium ; sed ex multis particularibus in quibus expertus sit, accipit unum commune quod firmatur in anima, et considerat illud absque consideratione alicujus singularium, et hoc accipit ut principium artis et scientiae. Puta, diu medicusconsideravit hanc herbam sanasse Socratem febrien- tem, et Platonem, et multos alios singulares homines ; cum autem sua consideratio ad hoc ascendit quod talis species herbae sanat febrientem simpliciter, hoc accipitur ut quaedam regula artis medicinae " (St. Thomas, in loc. cit.). It will be observed that there is no mention here of " Inductio " but only of " Experimentum ". It is significant, too, that these passages from Aristotle and St. Thomas are from the Posterior Analytics, i.e. from that part of the Organon which treats of Certain Science, while the passages quoted above in reference to enumerative induction — complete and incomplete — are taken from the Prior Analytics and the Topics, i.e. the parts that refer, the one to the formal side of reasoning, the other to probable arguments. INDUCTION IN ITS VARIOUS SENSES 35 But another leading Scholastic, Duns Scotus, has analysed with a good deal of precision the procedure by which the general ization is effected. When a phenomenon occurs repeatedly under the influence of a cause that is not free, we must conclude, he teaches, that the effect in question has a " natural " connexion with the cause. . . . For it is impossible that a necessary cause produce the same effect regularly, unless it is determined by its natural tendency — its directive principle or form, as he calls it — to produce this effect. The effect must spring from the nature of that cause and not from any accidental, concomitant agencies ; for accidental agencies do not produce regular effects. And that any such regular series of effects is due to the nature of a certain cause, we know from experience : because we have seen this cause followed by these effects, when acting now in one set of conditions, again in a different set, and altogether in many varieties of cir cumstances,1 Thus, Scotus points out as the rational, self- evident basis of induction, the judgment that what REGULARLY results front the action of NON-FREE causes cannot be the result of mere CHANCE, but must have a necessary connexion with the NATURE of those causes ; and he furthermore points to the neces sity of varying our experiences, in order to separate, from the changing and accidental circumstances that accompany the ap pearance of the phenomenon in question, the one agency or group of agencies on which it is really dependent, which forms its real cause : a plain application of the modern Method of Agreement. Why, then, it may be asked, did the Scholastics of the Middle Ages, if they knew the theory of scientific induction, and the principle underlying it, not proceed to apply the method, and so anticipate by centuries the wonderful 1 " De cognitis per experientam dico, quod licet experientia non habeatur de om nibus singularibus, sed de pluribus, nee quod semper, sed quod pluries ; tamen expertus infallibiliter novit, quod ita est, et quod semper et in omnibus ; et hoc per istam propositionem quiescentem in anima : QUIDQUID EVENIT UT IN PLURIBUS AB ALIQUA CAUSA NON LIBERA, EST EFFECTUS NATURALIS ILLIUS CAUSAE. Quae pro- positio nota est intellectui, licet accepisset terminos ejus a sensu errante, quia causa non libera non potest producere ut in pluribus effectum, ad cujus oppositum ordinatur, vel ad quern ex forma sua non ordinatur . . . sed causa casualis ordinatur adprodu- cendum oppositum effectus naturalis, vel non ad istum producendum, ergo nihil est causa casualis respectu effectus frequenter producti ab eo, et ita si non est libera, est naturalis. . . . Quod autem iste effectus evenit a tali causa producente ut in pluribus, hoc acceptum est per experientiam ; quia inveniendo nunc talem naturam cum tali accidenie. nunc cum tali, inventum est, quod, quantumcumque esset diversitas acci- dentium talium, semper istam naturam sequebatur talis effectus. Ergo non per aliquod accidens, per accidens illius naturae, sed per naturam ipsam in se conse- quitur tallis effectus" (In. /. Sent. dist. iii., Q. iv, 9). 3* 36 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC strides which physical science has made since the Renaissance ? Many good reasons may be assigned. One is that in those ages philosophers were more preoccupied with the philosophy of mind than with that of external nature, with the application of reason to principles accepted on authority, with the explanation of revealed religion and the unfolding of the contents of the Divine deposit of Revelation by means of philosophical principles and methods (203). And, as the full mean ing and proper understanding of those great truths and principles are arrived at by the application of the deductive or synthetic method, the attention of those philosophers was not arrested ^y the possibilities of knowledge that might have been opened up through a more careful analysis of the complex phenomena of external nature.1 But another, and more important, consideration is that they had not the means of prosecuting such an analysis. They knew the method theoretically, but this knowledge in itself was of little use. When there is question of estab lishing a law of Physical Nature — such as the laws of the planetary motions, or of the refraction of light — it is not enough to know that " a non-free cause cannot regularly produce an effect that is opposed to its natural tendency, an effect it is not determined by its nature to produce," — " causa non libera non potest producere ut in pluribus effectum, ad cujus oppositum ordinatur, vel ad quern ex forma sua non ordinatur ". This abstract, hypothetical principle merely asserts that if " necessary " or " non-free " causes exist, causes predis posed by an internal tendency ("forma ") to produce definite effects, the latter will occur with the regularity of a " law " ; but it does not of itself authorize us to assert categorically that there are such internal tendencies or principles of finality in nature, that there are causes predisposed to manifest such fixed, unchanging activities (cf. 223) ; and still less to affirm with certainty that this or that oft-observed combination of particular phenomena is the expression of some one of those causal tendencies existing in nature. Such a categorical conclusion as the latter can be justified only by a dili gent observation of the natural phenomena to which it refers. And nature is infinitely complex : so that the establishment of a certain conclusion that this series of phenomena reveals this universal physical law, necessarily presup poses a detailed and accurate weighing, reasoning, analysing, and comparing of all the elements that enter into the phenomena in question. The phe nomena of physical nature exist in space and time : accurate quantitative measurement is, therefore, at the basis of all experimental research : and hence, the discovery of instruments for delicate measurement was an indispensable condition for the progress of the physical sciences. But Aristotle and the mediaeval Scholastics had neither the clock for the accurate measurement of time, nor the balance for the exact estimation of weight, nor the thermometer for measuring temperature, nor the barometer for measuring atmospheric pressure, nor the telescope to observe the heavens, nor the microscope to reveal the mysteries of the minute structure and composition of organic tissues. It is true, indeed, that the sagacity of great genius, the patience of long reflection, and disinterested zeal in the pursuit of truth, can contribute much, even with the aid of mere ordinary observation, to the development of scientific speculation : witness the wonderful perfection of the Ptolemaic 1 Cf. CLARKE, Logic, p. 480. INDUCTION IN ITS VARIOUS SENSES 37 astronomy. Indeed the superior powers of Aristotle, and of his mediaeval Christian commentators, in the domain of ordinary, unaided observation, are undisputed at the present day. But it would be wrong to arrogate to them an honour they would be themselves the first to disclaim,— the honour of creat ing sciences which could not possibly have arisen without the invention of the special instruments of observation and measurement just referred to. Accurate experimentation was impossible in the Middle Ages, in the absence of those delicate means of weighing and measuring that are the inven tion of a more modern era. The thirteenth century, however, — the golden age of Scholasticism — produced at least one exceptional and extraordinary man, whose name cannot be passed over in connexion with the rise of scientific in duction. Roger Bacon, a Franciscan monk, who lived through the greater part of that century, dying at Oxford in 1 294, rose far above the commonplaces of his time in his advocacy of the experimental method. His life was one im passioned and even fanatical plea for the positive sciences. Nor did he con tent himself with pleading : he set an example by devoting his great genius to conducting scientific experiments and inventing instruments for that purpose. He distinguished four possible ways of gaining a knowledge of nature : authority, (a priori) reasoning, observation, and experiment. And he tells us that of these four the first ranks lowest in worth : " auctoritas debilior est ratione " ; the second, dialectic reasoning, does not satisfy the mind : " non certificat " ; nor the third, which is ordinary, superficial observation. The fourth alone — " internal " or " intrinsic " experience — is convincing, and that owing to the aid it receives from mathematics and geometry. He anticipated more renowned and more modern philosophers in an attempt to establish one general science that would submit to mathematical principles all the varied interactions of the bodies that make up the physical universe.1 209. LORD BACON'S " NOVUM ORGANON": THE Two IDEALS OF GENERALIZATION. — The English monk of the thir teenth century understood the nature and method of experimental science as well as, if not better than, his namesake of the six teenth. Francis Bacon, Lord Verulam (1561-1626), is commonly regarded as the " founder of the inductive method ". Wrongly, however ; because, in the first place, his method of " interpreting nature " has never been adopted : " The value of this method," writes Jevons,2 " may be estimated historically by the fact that it has not been followed by any of the great masters of science." Bacon blamed his predecessors, the " deductive " philosophers, for "anticipating" nature instead of " interpreting " it. After enumerating four great sources of such fallacious " anticipations " — the " Idola " or Phantoms : (a) of the Tribe (common to all men), (fr) of the Cave (due to personal idiosyncrasies), (c] of the Market- 1 Op. maj., p. iv., dist. i., c. iii., dist. ii.-iv. ; Opus tertium, c. 29-37, etc. ; cf. DELORME, Dictionnaire de theologie catholique, s.v. Bacon, 2 Principles of Science, p. 507. 38 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC Place (due to public catch-cries, shibboleths, etc.), ( verbal metaphor. There is a true and proper sense, as these philosophers contend, in which all created agencies act in fulfilment of purpose, in which "ALL agents act for an end " : " OMNE agens agit propter finem ". The conviction is gradually forced in upon us by our experi ence of natural phenomena, that every agency in nature must have some fixed, intrinsic principle of activity, in virtue of which it acts uniformly, and concurs with other physical agencies, not capriciously or indifferently, but along certain prearranged and predetermined lines ; so that " exceptions " to this uniformity must be due in reality to the influence of some unknown natural causes, or, possibly, to the intervention of the First Cause. Here, at all events, is the great fact we gather from sense experience : that very complex combinations of numerous natural agents re peatedly concur to produce uniform series of effects. Of this great fact there can apparently be one, and only one, rational in terpretation : that which conceives the proximate causes of such uniform series of phenomena as endowed each with a fixed natural inclination or tendency to act steadily and consistently along de finite lines, as having each an internal law which dominates it, and in conformity with which it will act always and everywhere. This innate, stable tendency is what the mind grasps when it apprehends the law of the Uniformity of Nature. The great fact of experience revealed in the regular, constant, harmonious concurrence of numerous and varied forces and agencies to produce uniform series of results, finds its sufficient reason and explanation only in a 1 The Essence of a thing (" Essentia " or " Quidditas ") is that which makes the thing what it is (" id quo res est id quod est " : the answer to the question " Quid est ilia res'} "). The Nature (" Natura ") is the essence itself looked on as the directive principle of the thing's activities (the " principium operationis "). It was conceived by the Scholastics as the impression of a divine directive plan or design on the inner constitution of the created agency : "Stabilis inclinatio vel appetitus finis, rebus a Deo inditus" or again, " Ars quaedam Divina indita rebus, per quam ad fines pro- prios non solum ducuntur sed quodammodo vadunt." — St. Thomas, Q(^. DD. De Veritatc, Q. xxii, a. i. 5* 68 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC fixed NATURAL INCLINATION or tendency of the agents which pro duce such results. The expression " natural inclination " embodies a fundamental doctrine of Aristotelean philosophy ; it implies that the agencies whose effects or manifestations we observe in the world around us are not, as the advocates of mechanical de terminism (215) would have them, mere efficient agents capable of producing any or every result indifferently, but that each of them is endowed with an internal tendency in virtue of which it manifests a manner of being and acting proper to itself; which manner is called a property of the substance, and reveals the specific nature of this latter. This view of the universe, as the expression of a divine plan, — hence called ideological, — renders intelligible the use of a term that is constantly recurring in the logic of induction : the term Law (Lex). Law means primarily an order, mandate, precept, emanating from the will of a superior (the legislator), and imposed upon a community subject to him.1 The law, as abiding in their minds and hearts, by their knowledge of it and submission to it, secures a certain uniformity in their conduct: it becomes the immediate source and principle, in them, of a series of similar acts. Next, the term Law came to be applied to what was really its effect, to this uniform series of similar acts. It was then extended, in this latter sense, from the domain of human activity to the domain of physical, even inanimate, nature ; and here it is now used, as, for example, in all the " physical " and " natural " 2 sciences, to denote any uniform series of connected phenomena, whether the connected elements exist simultaneously (" coexist ences ") or successively (" sequences "). The general propositions or statements which formulate such connexions are commonly referred to as "laws of physical nature": e.g. "Water seeks its own level," " All bodies fall with the same acceleration in a vacuum," "At a given temperature the volume of a given quantity of gas varies inversely as the pressure it sustains," " Heat can produce mechanical work, and vice versa, in definite, measurable proportions," "The strength of an electric current varies directly as the electromotive force and inversely as the resistance," "Every living cell has its origin from some other living cell," "Fermentation is due to the action of microbes". 1 Cf. The Inductive Sciences, etc., pp. 70 sqq. a These terms are commonly regarded as synonymous ; when they are distin guished, the former refers to the sciences of inorganic, inanimate nature, the latter to those of the living universe, CONCEPTS OF "REASON" AND "CAUSE" 69 Most of these "laws" are merely formulae descriptive of con stant connexions which have been discovered to exist between phenomena, and of the conditions and circumstances in which such connexions are found to obtain. But those uniform happen ings must, after the analogy of the uniform conduct of a com munity subject to the law of a superior, be themselves due to fixed principles of action inherent in the constitution of the natural agencies which manifest those uniform activities. Now, if we bring to light the agencies which are operative — and co-operative — in producing those regular coexistences and sequences, the mode of action and interaction of the efficient causes that are at work, the inner constitution or nature of those agencies, i.e. their material and formal causes, and the scope or purpose of those activities, we can formulate explanatory or causal laws, i.e. laws which will not merely express the existence of uniformities, but which, furthermore, will give us an insight into the "how" and the "why" of such uniformities (222). The Aristotelean conception and classification of causes, and the Scholastic view of physical nature as a " cosmos," revealing purpose, design, intelligence, and subject to " law " in the sense just explained, have been almost completely ignored by modern exponents of the logic of induction.1 Some of these latter have substituted a purely mechanical view of the universe, eliminating the notions of " design " and " efficiency " as superfluous, and retaining merely the notions of " invariable " or " necessary " " sequences " and " coexistences " of material phenomena, as the ultimate factors of a rational explanation of the universe. These writers have been induced by a rather superficial materialism to abandon, and even to ridicule, the r61e of final causes in philosophical research. Yielding too hastily to the natural craving for a simple solution of the problems raised by the universe, they have thought to satisfy themselves and others by proclaiming the sufficiency of physical efficient causality, i.e. of invariable connexions between masses of matter in motion, for the adequate explanation of all things. The attempt was necessarily futile, and is nowadays generally recognized as such. " The mechanical theory of the universe," writes Professor Welton,2 " is simple, but inadequate even in inorganic nature ; in organic nature it must be supplemented by the principle of development, and finally by the conception of rational purpose." To which we may add Mr. Joseph's testimony,3 that " to a physical theory of the world consciousness remains unaccountable ; such a theory therefore cannot be complete or final ". We shall see later (219, 224) that the "necessity" of those "uniform con nexions " or " laws " can have no rational basis in the " mechanical " view of nature. Neither, however, does it receive a satisfactory explanation on the Hegelian, idealist view, that nature is merely a system of thought-relations ; and that its "necessities" are identical with the necessities of thought (215). 1 Cf. VENN, Empirical Logic, pp. 47-52. 8 Logic, ii., pp. 206, 210; cf. p. 30 (italics ours). sop. cit., p. 384. 70 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC Writers who support this latter view bring out very clearly the shortcomings of Empiricism ; l but, though they rightly include the concept of " final cause " i.e. of purpose, design, in their philosophical explanation of natural phenomena, they still fail to recognize explicitly the " formal " and " material " causes, as distinct from the "efficient causes," of phenomena, and are thus led to identify the cause with the process, and this latter with the effect. In most of the physical sciences we are mainly concerned with the dis covery and explanation of processes, changes, motions, activities, actions and interactions between material agencies : and our main concern here must be to find out what are the proximate agencies at work in a given process, to separate these from irrelevant and accidental surroundings, to detect the total (proximate) agens and the total (proximate) pattens in question, and to discover and understand the connexion of physical efficient causality between these. But the discovery of a connexion of efficient causality, of action and interaction, between physical agents, is the discovery of active and passive powers or properties in these agents : and the discovery of such properties or powers leads to a knowledge of the intrinsic constitution, the nature, of these agents. As a thing acts, so it is : Qua/is operatic, talis natura. All the insight we have into the inner nature and constitution of things is got by inference from their observed activities : Operari sequitur esse. And our knowledge of the inner nature and constitution of a physical cause, of the manner and conditions of its activities, will help us to understand its raison d'etre, its function or role in the universe, the purpose it serves, the end it is designed to fulfil, the final cause of the processes in which it plays a part. Thus we see that the search for any one class of cause is by no means incompatible with a search for the others. When one line of inquiry cannot be prosecuted, another may ; and each often helps the others. 2 1 8. CONTRAST BETWEEN TRADITIONAL AND EMPIRICAL CONCEPTIONS OF EFFICIENT CAUSALITY. — When the word "cause" is used without qualification "efficient cause" is meant. Used in this sense, the term " cause " has almost completely changed its traditional signification ; and with very confusing results. We must, therefore, note these changes of meaning carefully. The traditional notion of efficient cause is that of " anything which positively contributes by way of action or change or motion to the production or happening or existence of anything else". Positive influence by way of action is what we mean by the "effici ency " of a cause. This traditional conception of efficiency, or efficient causality, we can find no reason or justification for abandon ing. We shall therefore retain it. Furthermore, we must dis tinguish between the individual, substantial cause or agent itself (" the agens" the " principium quod agit ") ; the power, faculty, force, potential energy, of that cause (the "principium quo agens agit"); and the action ("actio") by which it produces its effect. 1 Cf. Professor WELTON'S criticisms of Mill, op. cit., passim. CONCEPTS OF " REASON " AND " CA USE ' ^ i And, of efficient causes themselves, we may distinguish several kinds : the First or Uncreated Cause, and second or created causes ; the free cause — which has the power of choice to act or not to act, which can determine itself to act or not, which has "do minion " or control of its act, — and the non-free or necessary or " natural" cause, — which, when placed in a definite set of circum stances, does always act, because it must act, because it has no power or control over its own act, but is by its very nature so constituted (by the First Cause) that (unless the First Cause miraculously interferes) it will, by a necessity of its nature, always act in those circumstances. Now, most modern writers on induction have come to use the terms cause, and efficient cause, in the sense of a non-free or necessary l cause. This in itself is not surprising, seeing that they have mainly, if not exclusively, in view the physical universe, inorganic and organic, exclusive of man ; and they may, perhaps, regard the adjective " physical," applied to " cause," as a suf ficient indication that they are dealing only with causes under stood to be connected "naturally" or "by a necessity of their nature " with their effects.2 With this usage, then, we will not quarrel, provided it be distinctly understood that there are, or may be, in existence, free causes. Where ambiguity would be likely to arise, we should use the adjectives " free " or " necessary ". An unfortunate result, however, of identifying efficient causality with the uniform causality of necessary causes, calls for notice here. It is the confusion of two quite distinct principles, the "principle of causality " (216) and the "principle of the uni formity of nature" (223), under the common title of the "law of universal causation ".3 But it is one assertion that " The same causes, acting in similar circumstances, will always produce the same effect " ; it is another and quite a different assertion that " Whatever happens has a cause ". The former, which is known as the " principle of the uniformity of physical nature," is not universally true, of all causes : as we shall see later (223), it applies, strictly speaking, only to "necessary" or "non-free" causes ; though it is often stated by modern writers in such a way as to insinuate that it is of universal application : which, of course, is tantamount to a denial of human free will. Similarly, 1 The term " necessitating" would convey the idea better than " necessary ". The latter term, however, can claim universal usage in this context. 8 Cf. JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 373. 3 Cy. MBLLONK, op. cit., p. 281. 72 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC the latter assertion — the self-evident principle of causality : " Every event necessarily has a cause " — is not to be confounded with this other altogether different assertion, that " Every event has a necessary cause ". This latter statement is not evident ; nay, it is not even true. Effects produced in the universe by the free activity of man have, manifestly, not necessary but free causes. Nevertheless, there are many modern writers on inductive logic, who in sinuate—perhaps unconsciously — in their whole doctrine of causality that the only concept of cause which is at all intelligible or amenable to scientific treat ment is the concept of a necessary or necessitating cause. Thus, Dr. Mellone refers to the self-evident principle of causality under the title of the Law of Universal Causation, and rightly remarks that it refers to " cause " in the widest sense : Every event must have some sort of cause, either a " necessary " (or " uniformly acting ") cause, or a " capricious " cause, or — he might add — a cause which, though free, is not " capricious," and about the operation of which we can consequently generalize with some degree of safety. " This principle [he writes] may be shown to be implied in all thinking. Even children and the lower races of men, though they do not think of it, think according to it. If the savage were content to leave any event unex plained, he would not imagine that all events are controlled by spirits, malevolent or benevolent. It is in fact IMPOSSIBLE TO THINK OF AN EVENT WITHOUT REFERRING IT TO A CAUSE, known or unknown. Even if we had a state of affairs where the past gave scarcely any assurance as to the future, our way of conceiving it would not be contrary to the principle of the universality of causation. We should think that some capricious power had added itself to the conditions, turning them now this way and now that." J All that is quite true ; for the word " cause " is clearly taken to include conditions, agencies, influences, and powers, of whatsoever kind, capricious and free no less than regular and necessary : on no other supposition indeed would the statement that " every event has a cause " be a self-evident axiom. But Dr. Mellone goes on immediately to say that the principle of the Uniformity of Nature, or " Uniformity of Causation" as he prefers to call it — that " the same cause must have the same effect "—a principle which will be shown to refer properly only to necessitating causes (223)— is included in the previous principle of the universality of causation, that " every event has a cause ". Surely this is not so. The universality of the law of causation throughout all contingent being, does not in itself imply that this causality is necessarily uniform. The self-evident principle of causality— that nothing can happen without a cause, ex nihilo nihil fit — understands " cause " in the widest conceivable sense of any real principle, whether free or mechanical, capricious or regular, which brings about the event : it has nothing to do with the question of repetition or regularity at all. Whereas Uniformity of Causa tion, even understood in the hypothetical sense in which Dr. Mellone takes it," bears exclusively upon regularity of repetition, and is self-evident only in re gard to non-free, or necessary causes, which are by nature so constituted 1 MELLONE, Introductory Text-book of Logic, pp. 280-1. *ibid., p. 282. CONCEPTS OF « REASON " AND " CVf £/.S£ " 73 and so endowed with one fixed tendency that in similar circumstances they must always produce similar effects. And yet Dr. Mellone continues : — " The student will see on reflection that this principle is included in the principle of universal causation ; for by cause is at least meant a condition on which the effect always follows. If it sometimes followed and sometimes did not, there would be no object in trying to discover it ; you would simply not have a cause at all." 1 No doubt we are free to define a cause as " a condition [or group of con ditions, agencies, influences] on which the effect always follows," and indeed this is the narrower sense in which the term is usually understood when we speak of the non-free causes that operate in external nature, the causes to which the principle of uniformity properly applies. But it is certainly not identical with the wider sense in which Dr. Mellone had rightly used the word when formulating the self-evident law of universal causation, that " every event has a cause," for in this latter context the term " cause " included free and even " capricious " causes. His final statement, that if the effect " sometimes followed and sometimes did not, . . . you would simply not have a cause at all," is quite too sweep ing. What is true, of course, is this, that we can infer or generalize about the operation, beyond experience, of any cause, only in so far as we are warranted in assuming its operation to be regular, not capricious. But if Dr. Mellone's statement were true, it would follow that man is not the cause of what he does freely, and that no science of human conduct is possible. This is one unsatis factory result of discarding the traditional notion of physical efficient causes as agencies or powers inherent in physical phenomena and productive of physical change, for the empiricist notion of such causes as " invariable and uncon ditional antecedents," i.e. phenomena or groups of phenomena " sufficient [or necessitating] and indispensable " for the appearance of other [consequent] phenomena. The " efficiency " of causation is quite a distinct concept from the " necessity " of causation. Yet these are sometimes confounded. Professor Welton, for example, criticizing Mill's account of causality, writes 2 that the latter " finds cause in a set of conditions whose existence necessitates that of the effect," and he adds immediately that " greater efficiency than this no one would wish to establish ". But efficiency is not necessity. A cause may be efficient and yet not be necessitating, but free. In fact it is from our con- 1 MELLONE, ibid., p. 281. Mr. JOSEPH (op. cit., pp. 370 sqq.) adopts the same view : " There is no need then to distinguish the law of causation from the uniformity of nature ; for — bating the possible exception of the causality of the human will — a cause which does not act uniformly is no cause at all ; and if we are looking for the presuppositions of inductive inference it is plain that the only con nexions whose existence would justify such inference are uniform connexions" (P- 376)- '2 Logic, ii., p. 19. Mr. Joseph makes a similar mistake about the verb produce : " to say that anything may produce anything is to empty the verb ' produce ' of all its meaning. For the causal relation is a necessary relation, such that if you have one thing you must have another. To add that it does not matter what the other is, destroys the force of the must " (p. 374). No doubt it destroys the force of the "must"; but surely "must" is different from "produce," and this again from " necessarily produce ". 74 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC sciousness of our own free volitional activity that we derive the notion of efficiency in the first instance. Efficiency we conceive as positive influence in the production of changes or effects by the exertion of power or force. The earliest efficient causality of which we become aware is our own free efficient causality. Then we come to conceive external nature as also endowed with powers or forces, as efficient in the production of changes or effects. Of course there have been and are philosophers who maintain that belief in real efficiency in nature is an illusion ; and some have extended their denial even to the domain of mind as well. Occasionalists take up this attitude on the ground that efficient causality is essentially an attribute of the Creator, incom municable to the creature. This view does not concern us here. Our present purpose is merely to emphasize an obvious distinction between the notion of efficient cause — whether free or necessary— and the notion of uniform con nexion — whether of coexistence or sequence — between phenomena ; and to point out that it is exclusively to the latter concept Empiricists apply the terms " causation " or " causality ". For the rest, as far as the theory of physical induction is concerned, this later usage is not without its conveniences ; for in the first place, it is regularity, uniformity, invariability of the connexion between physical causes and their effects, that forms the real objective ground of our generalizations and inferences about them : 1 not the inner nature of that connexion itself. And secondly, I if the physical scientist sets up as his ideal the discovery of the perceptible ante cedents, or groups of antecedents, which are sufficient and indispensable for the production of certain phenomena — so as to be able to apply this knowledge in bringing such phenomena about— as in engineering and the other applied sciences— the ideal is a perfectly legitimate one.2 Only, if he is himself thus con tent with the discovery of proximate, perceptible antecedents, he must not deny l the possibility of prosecuting the search for remoter, non-perceptible agencies.3 And if he bestows on those visible groups of" invariable and unconditional ante cedents " the title of "causes," we need not object to this — for they are de facto " causes,"— though we have, perhaps, some reason to complain that he is changing the traditional meaning of an important term without sufficient justifica tion : even were there no such things in existence as causes in the traditional sense of the term, he would not refute the traditional belief by merely changing the definition of the name. We agree with Mr. Joseph that the freedom of the human will is a difficult problem, not to be argued here.4 And the same may be said of " efficiency ". But to deny to free will the title of " cause " does not solve the problem or prove free will to be a fiction. At all events men generally believe that they are free agents, and that they freely " cause " or '•'•produce " effects. In the face of this fact we see no adequate reason to justify the logician in asserting absolutely and without qualification that " causa! connexions are necessary and universal," or that " to assert causation is to assert uniformity of connexion ".6 The logician must take into account not merely the domain of physical nature, lCf. VENN, Empirical Logic, pp. 50, 51, 93; MILL, Logic, iii., v., § 2. "Cf. JOYCE, op. cit., p. 223. . 3" I premise, then, that when ... I speak of the cause of any phenomenon, ^ I do not mean a cause which is not itself a phenomenon." — MILL, Logic, iii., v., § 2. *op. cit., p. 373. *ibid., p. 375 (italics ours). CONCEPTS OF " REASON " AND " CA USE " 75 but likewise the domain of human activity (201). Nor should he identify physical science with science simply : " If the non-mechanical conditions upon which physical changes depend (supposing that such there are) cannot be as certained and formulated in a way which enables physical science to take ac count of them, it will treat them as non-existent. It is of no use to regard a factor, whose mode of action is unascertainable. It must remain for science — what the will is upon one theory of human freedom — a source of purely incalculable and to it irrational interference. But irrational interference is just what cannot be supposed to occur. No doubt an interference which admits an explanation according to law is not irrational ; but if the law is unascertainable, it is as good as irrational. And this attitude of physical science has the practical justi fication, that if events are once admitted to occur in the material order whose conditions are unascertainable within that order, there is no point at which we can draw the line. Only by assuming that it can explain everything is it possible to find out how much it can explain in physical terms." 1 For the credit of physical science itself we should be sorry to find any of its students claim such pretensions for it as the author here attempts to justify (201). The physical scientist may, of course, legitimately abstract from the existence of " non- mechanical conditions," but he may not gratuitously deny their existence. Surely, too, a " factor " may be " unascertainable," in the sense of being " incalculable " in terms of material atoms and motion, may not admit of " explanation according to " mechanical " law," and yet need not be, or be called, " irrational," or " as good as irrational ". Is that alone "rational " which is " mechanical " ? or is there no " law," no " explanation," for what is not mechanical ? Surely this is a vast and gratuitous assumption for anyone to make, whether in the name of physical science or on any other pretext. We fail to see why the physical scientist must deny that " events " may and do " occur in the material order whose conditions are unascertainable within that order ". The man who ventures on such a denial would evince more daring than science. Finally, can science " find out how much it can explain " only " by assuming that it can explain everything " ? Again we must confess our failure to see the necessity of any such extraordinary assumption. Bearing those few cautions in mind, we may now glance at the growth of some prevalent views about physical causality. 219. THE SENSIST OR EMPIRICAL VIEW OF CAUSALITY: MILL'S TEACHING.— John Locke (1632-1704) had taught that causality, or the power to produce change, was not " contained in the real existence of things, but . . . extraneous and super induced " — i.e. by the consideration of the mind. But causality in things seems to be as real as their substantiality, nay, as their very existence. Accordingly, either causality is real or all reality is simply a subjectively fabricated idea. The latter alter native was practically accepted by David Hume (1711-1776), who reduced all reality to a series of subjective feelings or states lop. cit., p. 386. 76 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC of consciousness ; causality thus becoming a mere feeling of ex pectation of invariable succession in certain of those states — a conviction or belief resulting from the association of repeated experiences. Though some of Hume's followers renounced the subjectivity of this view, all alike clung to the notion of invariable sequence of phenomena in time as constituting the essence of causality. " The cause" [of any physical fact, event, phenomenon], writes John Stuart Mill1 (1806-1873) "is the sum total of the conditions, positive and negative taken together . . . which being realized, the consequent invariably follows. . . . The negative conditions . . . may be all summed up under one head, namely, the absence of preventing or counteracting causes." Here we have the cause of a phenomenon described as that total group of antecedents which, whenever it is realized, is always followed by that pheno menon. But day is invariably followed by night ; yet we do not call it the " cause " of night. Nor do we call night the " cause " of day, though it has been invariably followed by day. This is so, Mill goes on to say, because the 'sequence here is not absolutely or unconditionally invariable : it is invariable only conditionally upon the conduct or activity of other things — upon the rising and setting of the sun in the case contemplated. But invariable sequence is not causality, he tells us, unless the invariability arises wholly and entirely from the nature of the phenomena themselves, is unconditioned by anything extrinsic to the latter, is altogether independent of "whatever supposition we may make with regard to other things," and will therefore obtain "under all imaginable circumstances " : that is, of course, " as long as the present con stitution of things " 2 endures. Such kind of invariable sequence he terms " unconditional " ; 3 and he then goes on to give his final and scientifically exact definition of " the cause of a phenomenon " as " the antecedent or concurrence of antecedents on which it [the phenomenon] is invariably and unconditionally consequent ". By thus defining causation as sequence which is invariable, not 1 Logic, III., v., § 3. Mill properly points out that popular usage generally fixes on some prominent one among those antecedents and applies to it exclusively the title of " cause ". 2 By this expression Mill tells us that he means " the ultimate laws of nature (whatever they may be) as distinguished from the derivative laws and from the col locations ". — op. dt., III., v., § 6. 3 Notwithstanding the condition just set down about the permanence of the " present constitution of things ". CONCEPTS OF " REASON " AND " CA USE " 77 by reason of any extrinsic conditions, but unconditionally and by reason of the nature of the phenomena themselves which constitute the sequence, Mill evidently intended to convey that an antecedent, in order to be a "cause," must have a "necessary" connexion with its consequent. This conception of the "cause" of a phenomenon — as something which, of itself, of its own nature, and not by reason of any extrinsic conditions, is invariably followed by that phenomenon — is precisely what had suggested the traditional notion of a necessary as opposed to a free cause : we are prompted to regard a cause as necessarily productive of an effect by observing it to be always and in all circumstances followed by that effect. By making the invariability of the con nexion independent of all other conditions, and thus, as the only alternative, dependent on the nature of the connected phenomena themselves, Mill believed that he was giving intelligible ex pression to " what writers mean when they say that the notion of cause involves the idea of necessity. If there be any meaning which confessedly belongs to the term necessity, it is unconditionalness. That which is necessary, that which must be, means that which will be, whatever supposition we may make in regard to all other things. The succession of day and night evidently is not necessary in this sense. It is conditional on the occurrence of other antecedents. That which will be followed by a given consequent when, and only when, some third circumstance also exists, is not the cause, even though no case should ever have occurred in which the phenomenon took place without it. ... Let me add that the antecedent which is only conditionally invariable, is not the invariable antecedent [in the full sense of absolutely invariable — in the future as in the past ?]. Though a fact may in experience have always been followed by another fact, yet if the remainder of our experience teaches us that it might not always be so followed, or if the experience itself is such as leaves room for a possibility that the known cases may not correctly represent all possible cases, the hitherto invariable antecedent is not accounted the cause ; but why ? Because we are not sure that it is the [really, absolutely, unconditionally] in variable antecedent "-1 But the idea of " necessity " is not the idea of actually uni form and unvaried sequence, though it is derived from our ex perience of the latter ; or of invariable sequence, except we take invariable to mean not only that which has not varied and does not and will not vary, but that which cannot vary. And in variability in this latter sense need not be at all unconditional in order to be described as " necessity," for the " necessity " itself may conceivably be conditional : we can quite conceive a sequence i ibid., 6. 78 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC which must remain unaltered so long as certain conditions are ful filled. This, in fact, is the only necessity experience warrants us in attributing to the sequences of nature ; and, as we shall presently see, Mill's so-called " unconditional " invariability re mained always ultimately " conditional ". How, then, it may be asked, from actual, limited experience of unvaried sequence in the past, can we get the idea of a sequence that is invariable — i.e. which " cannot " vary, which is " necessary " ? Let us first recall the tradi tional Scholastic account of " physical necessity," which is simple and intelli gible. " Necessity " may be either intellectual, hypothetical, abstract, connecting possible essences together in thought ; or it may be volitional, categorical, concrete, connecting actual things or occurrences together in reality. With this latter we are concerned here. When we speak of " that which must be " in reference to things or events, when we say that one thing must follow another, we can only mean that they are so constituted and circumstanced that by their very nature or constitution, and collocation, they cannot help following each other.1 Whatever Mill may say, no mere addition or multiplication of " was " and " is " and " will be " can ever generate an absolute or unconditional " must be ". What is there, then, in the observed unvaried uniformity of nature in the past, to warrant us in thinking not only that it will, but that it must, continue unvaried ? There is this : there is abundant evidence (of which the fact of observed uniformity itself forms a part) to warrant us in concluding with certitude that nature is the work of an All-Wise Creator and Ruler, who has so constituted and arranged its agencies that they will and must continue to exist and act, each in its own fixed, uniform way, as long as He chooses in His wisdom to preserve and sustain it in existence. Such is the uniformity, invariability, necessity, we ascribe to physical agencies : condi tional on the Will of an All-Wise, All-Ruling Providence.2 There is the ulti mate rational basis which analysis of human experience reveals for wx physical, conditional certitude about the general laws of physical science. Now let us observe and contrast the alternative offered by the empiricist philosophy of Mill and his school. The physical cause of a phenomenon, he writes, is that which has always " been followed by " that phenomenon in past experience, provided this experience does not leave any " room for a pos sibility that the known cases may not correctly represent all possible cases ". But if, as Mill's own philosophy teaches, we have no faculties of knowledge beyond our external and internal senses, whose only objects are sense- phenomena, associated, compounded, and otherwise modified in consciousness, how can the combination of past and present sense experience give us any 1 We abstract here, for the sake of simplicity, from the conditional necessity, called moral obligation, to which the conduct of free, responsible agents is subject. To these the Creator has given the power to act as they choose ; but He imposes on them a necessity by which they must (freely choose to) act in a certain way if they are to attain their end. But every non-free cause in animal, vegetable, and inor ganic creation, He has endowed with such a nature and constitution as categorically directs it to attain the end He has freely intended it to reach. 2 For a fuller development of these views on the necessity of physical laws and causes, cf. infra, Chap. IV., 224. CONCEPTS OF " REASON " AND " CA USE » 79 degree or kind of certitude, anything beyond a mere feeling of expectation that " all possible cases " will resemble the observed cases ? And even for this feeling of expectation Mill can offer us no rational ground whatsoever. He states that our actual experience enables us somehow to make up our minds that a given observed antecedent of a phenomenon will continue to be the antecedent of the latter unconditionally : which means " whatever sup position we may make about other things," or " under all imaginable circum stances ". But this he immediately limits and qualifies by saying that the antecedent will continue so only " as long as the present constitution of things endures" or as long as, and on condition that, " the ultimate laws of nature (whatever they may be)," do not -vary. So, after all, the "uncondi tional " invariability turns out to be conditional. Our sense experience of an unvaried sequence only enables us, therefore, to believe that the latter will continue unvaried, z/and as long as " the present constitution of things," " the ultimate laws of nature," will remain unaltered. And what rational ground\&.vt we, according to Mill, for believing that " the present constitution of things " will continue stable, and their " ultimate laws " unaltered ? He does not tell us ; and for a good reason : his philosophy affords none. It limits our knowledge to phenomena of sense ; it is agnostic : it informs us that we can know facts, but nothing about the inner nature and ultimate causes of those facts. And thus the empirical theory of induction, as of knowledge generally, destroys all certitude by rearing the whole edifice of physical science on the basis of an underlying confession of helpless and hopeless ignorance. In giving his final description of " cause " as the " uncondition ally " invariable antecedent, Mill explained that the " cause " must be not merely the hitherto invariable antecedent, but some thing which is the antecedent in "all possible cases". By this he has been commonly interpreted to mean that the " cause " in in the strict sense is the antecedent (or group of antecedents) which is not merely " sufficient " 1 but " indispensable " for the ap pearance of the consequent : not only the antecedent which is invariably followed by the consequent in question, but by which alone the consequent is invariably preceded : so that the invaria bility is on both sides, the relation is a reciprocal one, and inference can proceed from effect to cause as well as from cause to effect. Thus we may distinguish, in Mill's account of causality, (i) the looser scientific concept of "cause" as the antecedent (or group of antecedents) which, when present, is always followed by a certain consequent ; (2) the still looser popular concept of " cause " as denoting some one prominent element of that group (abstracting from the others) ; (3) the stricter and more exact 1 In the sense of " necessitating ". This is the meaning commonly attached to the word in regard to physical causes. A free cause may be " sufficient " (in the ordinary sense of the word) to produce an effect, and yet not necessitate that effect. 8o THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC scientific concept of " cause " as the antecedent which is not only always followed by the consequent in question, but which is the only antecedent so followed : not only the sufficient, but the indispensable, antecedent of that consequent.1 220. CAUSALITY, SEQUENCE IN TIME AND CONTIGUITY IN SPACE. — Mill's account is intelligible so far as it goes. He has, of course, never succeeded in assigning any ultimate rational ex planation of the fact that natural causes and their .effects are connected in the uniform, unchanging, " invariable " manner in dicated by him. Apart from this defect, however, which is due to his empiricist theory of knowledge, there is the erroneous im plication that time sequence is essential to causality, that two phenomena cannot be related as cause and effect unless they succeed each other in time. Now, efficient physical causality does not necessarily imply that the cause must totally precede the effect in time. Even popular thought, which seizes on one prominent, partial element in the total cause — often a remote element — and on a similar element in the effect, does not regard " cause " and " effect " as separate, successive events, but only as distinct : the immediate cause and the immediate effect are always thought of as con nected. The link connecting them — the causation, action, change, or process, as it is variously called — goes on in time and occupies time. The immediate cause, therefore, cannot entirely precede, but must also coexist with, the immediate effect. The producing cause and the produced effect must be simultaneous, for they are 1 C/. JOSEPH, op. cit., pp. 64, 65 — " When we call one thing [i.e. kind of thing] the cause of another, the real relation between them is not always the same ... we say that molecular motion is the cause of heat, that the heat of the sun is the cause of growth, that starvation is sometimes the cause of death, that jealousy is a fre quent cause of crime. We should in the first case maintain that the cause and effect are reciprocally necessary ; no heat without molecular motion and no molecular motio^ without heat. In the second the effect cannot exist without the cause, but the cause may exist without the effect; for the sun shines on the moon but nothing grows there. In the third, the cause cannot exist without the effect, for starvation must produce death, but the effect may exist without the cause, since death need not have been produced by starvation. In the fourth case we can have the cause without the effect, and also the effect without the cause ; for jealousy may exist without producing crime, and crime may occur without the motive of jealousy. It is plain, then, that we do not always mean the same thing by our words, when we say that two things are related as cause and effect ; and any one who would classify and name the various modes in which two things maybe causally related would do a great service to clear thinking." And the author adds : " that is the sort of service that Aristotle attempted in distinguishing the heads of predic- ables ". C/. also op. cit., c. xxii. CONCEP TS OF « RE A SON " A ND " CA USE " 8 1 correlative. If the cause ceases to act, then the effect ceases to be produced; for the "action" (actio, facere] of the cause and the " production " (passio, fieri) of the effect are one and the same process of real change. Hence the Scholastic axiom " Cessante causa, cessat effectus ". The act of " taking poison " may have ceased long before " death " occurs ; but the poison, once introduced into the system, continues to exist and to operate, effecting changes which in turn cause other changes, until finally a condition of the organism is reached, which is so striking, familiar, and significant that it has received a special title to indicate it, viz. death. The first " act," and the final " state " or effect, are, therefore, connected by a continuous process of natural causation, each stage of which is both an effect (of the preceding one) and a cause (of the subse quent one) ; and wherever we draw a line of distinction in this process of change, the state of things on the one side of the line is the immediate cause, of which the contiguous state on the other side is the immediate effect. " Cause and effect," writes Dr. Mellone,1 " are divided by a simple mathe matical line — a line destitute of breadth — which is thrown by our thought across the current of events ; on one side we have the cause, on the other the effect. There is no pause in reality ; the whole process is continuous ; the immediate cause conies into full action only at the very moment when the effect begins to be produced. The point to be borne in mind is the continuity of cause and effect." The whole process of change in the occurrence of any physical phenomenon is, therefore, continuous : there is one continued " motus " or motion throughout : this motion may be regarded either from the point of view of its origin, or from that of its termination : it will be called action (" actio ") when looked at from the side of the cause or agens from which it originates, and "passio " when looked at from the side of the effect or pattens in which it terminates. The Scholastics marked and emphasized their appreciation of the unity and continuity of the whole process by crystallizing their view in the dictum " Actio et passio sunt idem numero motus" : " Acting" and " being acted on " are one and the same real "motion," looked at from different standpoints. But the Scholastics were at N the same time careful not to confound the actual process of change (" fieri ") either with the efficient causes themselves on the one hand, or with the stable 1 op. dt., p. 273. VOL. II. 6 82 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC result of the change (the effect "in facto esse"} on the other. They rightly distinguished in every such process the (material) substances or agents at work (substantial causes), the forces or powers (proximate principles of action) through which those agents or causes act, and the action or process of change itself (218). They distinguished, furthermore, between the extrinsic causes (efficient andjinaf), which they called " causes of the actual change" (i.e. of the "fieri" ex production of the effect), and the intrinsic causes (formal and material] which they called (con stitutive) causes of the produced result or effect, in its completed state (" in facto esse ".) * Ignoring those distinctions, modern writers have fallen into the error of actually identifying the " efficient cause " with its " effect," by regarding each as a mere aspect of the process of change itself, and this latter, ap parently, as the sole reality. For example, Professor Welton2 arrives at this conclusion : " Cause and effect are not two but one. That they are in separable is indeed recognized by the relativity of the very terms themselves. A cause without an effect or an effect without a cause is a contradiction in terms and unthinkable. But we must go farther and say that in content they are absolutely identical. It is only in form that they can be distinguished and then we may speak of the one as determining and of the other as deter mined. Thus the combination of hydrogen and oxygen in the quantitative ratio of two to one determines that the effect shall be water, and the character of that effect is determined by the character of the elements which are com bined, but the combined elements and the water are one and the same identical substance, and this substance is the content both of the cause and of the effect." This is indeed going very far ; much too far. To identify the efficient cause with its effect, the "producer" with the "produced," is not only setting popular thought and belief at defiance, but even espousing the implicit contra diction that an effect can produce itself. When, therefore, we come to reflect on the immediateness of the cause to the effect, we see that while the scientist must indeed aim at grasping the former as closely as possible to the latter, in order to be sure of including every indis pensable factor in the former, and so attaining as closely as he may to the ideal of a reciprocal causal relation, he must guard equally against identifying the cause with the effect, under pain of making all experimental search for " causes " meaningless and impossible. For, if the effect is identical with the cause, then when we know the effect we know the cause, and there can be no meaning in searching for the latter. Our " reciprocal relation " appears to have become a mere tautology ; " The statement that cause and effect are ' identical ' . . . becomes an extravagant paradox if taken seriously and applied to any particu lar case of causation determined by scientific experiment ".3 1 C/. ST. THOMAS, Summa Theol., i., q. 101, Art. i \-apud JOYCE, op. cit.t p. 248. *Op. cit. ii., p. 25. * MELLONB, op. ctt., p. 274. CONCEPTS OF " REASON " AND " CA USE " 83 This confusion of cause with effect arises from losing sight of the categoiy of substance, and of the all-important Scholastic distinctions between agent and action, and between extrinsic (efficient) and intrinsic (formal and material) causes l (216, 218). These distinctions are real; they are in the reality ; they are not merely mental or logical, different ways of regarding one and the same reality. In all processes of physical change the formal and material causes are intrinsic to, and identical with, the interacting agents, because they con stitute these latter. In the change by which oxygen and hydrogen produce water, the two former are materially identical with the latter, but then they differ formally (in their " formal " or " specifying " causes) from the latter and from each other. " The combined elements and the water are one and the same identical substance " ; but if they are, they are really different from the separate elements, for these on combining, on becoming water, on assuming the " form " or " specifying principle " of water, lost the " forms " of oxygen and hydrogen respectively. If the water were really identical with the oxygen and hydrogen, the change would not have been real but merely mental : that is to say, the processes of external nature would not be real but illusory : the only real change taking place would be the change involved in the logical process of the thinking mind. And this, in fact, is what the advocates of Hegelian idealism profess to believe (215). Similarly, physical causes occupy space and act in space, but that con tiguity in space, direct or indiiect contact, is essential to their activity, is not clearly evident. That there is and must be a connexion of some sort, in reality as well as in thought, between cause and effect, is undeniable. But is actio in distans, i.e. across empty space or vacuum, metaphysically 01 physically impossible ? We know too little about the nature of matter, space, and material action or motion, to give a categorical and decided answer to either part of the question. " How can a body act where it is not ? " Professor Wei- ton repeats the old puzzling query,2 and hazards an answer. But would it not be as well honestly to confess our ignorance of the " how " — remembering that this does not prove impossibility — as to say that the body is there, where its influence is felt, "in one very true and important sense of its reality " — in the sense of exerting influence there — while it is not present there, but absent from there, and present in another place, " in another sense of its reality — the sense in which reality is identified with visible and tangible form and tangible resistance "? What then is space? — if different "senses" or " aspects " of a body's reality may be in different parts of it ? The author does not inform us ; though, a few pages further on,3 he seems to reduce all physical efficient activity to local motion, and this latter to change of " spatial relations ". This reduction of even qualitative and substantial changes in physical nature to mechanical or local change has only its simplicity to 1 Cf. JOSEPH, Logic, p. 451. 2o/>. cit., pp. 20, 21. 3 ibid., p. 24 : " When it is said in this connexion [in mechanics, regarding the conservation of energy] that 'the cause equals the effect,' the 'cause' spoken of is not a thing but the efficient action of a thing, and this action reduces itself to its permanent attributes in a certain spatial relation to the object on which it acts ". The efficient action of a physical cause is thus analysed into certain permanent at tributes of that cause, plus certain spatial relations between it and the "object" upon which it is conceived to " act ". 6* 84 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC recommend it (217). It explains nothing adequately ; and it is in fact rejected as inadequate by the author himself in a subsequent chapter of his logic.1 221. " PLURALITY OF CAUSES " : " RECIPROCAL " AND " NON- RECIPROCAL" CAUSAL RELATIONS. — We have seen, so far, that the term " cause " has a multiplicity of kindred meanings : that besides the " formal " and " material " causes, or intrinsic consti tutive principles of the visible, material agencies in nature, and besides the " final " causes, " ends " or " purposes " for which these act, there are also these agents themselves, which we have called ' ' efficient " causes. We have distinguished between these efficient causes and the " action " or " motion " or " process " by which they produce their effects. We have also distinguished between efficient causes that are " free " or " self-determining " and efficient causes that are " necessary " or " necessitating " ; and we have seen that we can lay down general propositions about the mode of operation of efficient causes throughout space and time only in so far as we are convinced that those causes act uniformly beyond the range of our own actual sense ex perience (218); observing that this uniformity, though not absent from the domain of free causes, is much more prevalent and reliable in the domain of " necessary " causes — that is, in the physical sciences, with which induction is mainly concerned (218, cf. 223). We have seen too that, generally speaking, every class or kind of phenomenon in nature results from the convergence and combination of numerous influences, agencies, and condi tions, which are collectively "sufficient" (or "necessitating") and severally "indispensable" for the production of that special kind of phenomenon (216). The multiplicity and variety of these conditions, and their inseparable connexion with conditions not needed for the production of this kind of phenomenon, render it difficult for science to sift out and group together as the " cause" of the phenomenon, just those influences and those only which are sufficient and indispensable for its production. Com bined with this difficulty of bringing to light the " cause" in this narrower and stricter sense of reciprocal cause (cf. 213), we have the consideration that from the practical point of view — i.e. of producing or preventing effects — acquaintance with a plurality of alternative " causes," in the wider sense of " sufficient " though not "indispensable" modes of producing that sort of effect, is more important and more desirable than an exact knowledge of 1 op. cit., pp. 209, 210. Cf. JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 382. CONCEPTS OF "REASON" AND "CAUSE" 85 the one "reciprocal" or "commensurate" cause of that effect. Hence the question arises, whether Science ought to aim at the discovery of reciprocating causal relations, or merely of causal relations such that although the "cause" will necessitate the " effect," this latter will not necessitate the former, but admit of a " Plurality of Causes " (cf. 138). If we take a " physical "or " necessary " " cause " in the popular sense of some prominent or striking event which, when it happens, is always followed by another remarkable event (the "effect"), it will be evident that though the same natural cause, acting in similar circumstances (e.g. administering deadly poison), always produces the same effect (e.g. death), nevertheless the same effect (death) need not be always produced by the same cause (poison) : that although " effect " can be inferred from " cause "- "posita causa, ponitur effectus" — still the converse, " cause " from " effect " — "posito ejfectu, ponitur causa " — cannot be lawfully in ferred. And the reasdn is that in this sense of the term " cause," the same " effect " may be produced by different " causes " : that one and the same effect — death, for example — may be due to any one or more of an indefinite multitude of " causes ". We speak popularly of an agency as the "natural cause" of a given result or effect, provided that this agency be sufficient (or necessitating] — even though it be not indispensable, in the sense of being the only possible agency — for the production of such an effect. And formal logic, recognizing this mode of thought and expression, and ap plying the Law of Parsimony (94), prohibits the simple conver sion of the conditional proposition, which connects cause with effect as logical antecedent with consequent, as reciprocal (140). If, therefore, we take the terms "physical cause" and "effect" in this practical meaning, the former as that which always and necessarily produces the latter, and the latter as that which is produced, no doubt, by the former, but which is or may be produced otherwise as well, then it will be true to say that one and the same " effect " may have a plurality of " causes," though one and the same (natural or necessary) " cause " cannot have a plurality of " effects "-1 1 Evidently, the co-operation or " composition " of many partial causes may contribute to the production of one single effect : e.g. a person's death may be due to a complication of diseases no single one of which would separately have proved fatal (cf. 244). But " composition " of (partial) causes is quite a different thing from "plurality of causes". The latter means that one and the same effect (death) may, in different instances, be produced by entirely different total causes (poison, shooting, smallpox, old age, etc.). 86 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC On the other hand, were we to understand by the " cause " of a given kind of event not any and every factor (or group of fac tors) capable of producing it, but that precise factor (or group), and that only, which (being present in all modes of producing it) is itself capable, and alone capable, of producing the event, then this kind of event can be produced by that one " cause," and by it alone. In other words, no event can have a "plurality of causes " in this stricter sense of the term " cause V The doctrine that the same effect can have a " plurality of causes " holds good "as long as the 'cause* is understood in the popular way. The plurality disappears before any exact scientific investigation"? The subtraction of any factor from the " total cause " in this strict scientific sense, or the addition of any new factor to it, must necessarily modify the effect : no other factors or combinations of factors .could produce this sort of effect exactly and identically. This is but a simple application of the principle of identity. E is an effect whose total cause (or, the totality of whose sufficient and indispensable antecedents) is a + b + c. But, if it is so, it cannot at the same time, being and remaining identical with it self, be the result of a + b + c + d, or of a + b + d, or of a + 6, or of m + b + y, or of any other conceivable combination.3 222. SCIENCE AND THE DISCOVERY OF "CAUSES" AND " LAWS ". — In popular thought, therefore, the notion of " physical cause " usually includes elements not indispensable to the pro duction of the effect, though the notion of the " effect " does not include any element which is not necessitated by some element or other of the cause.4 The reason for this peculiar difference 1 The mediaeval Scholastics discussed " plurality of causes " in connexion chiefly with the individual effect, and the principle or ground of its individuation ; proposing the problem in terms like these : " Would Alexander the Great have been the same individual had he been born of other parents than Philip and Olympia ? " Their answer was usually in the negative. C/. ZIGLIARA, Ontologia (46), vii. 2MELLONE, op. cit., p. 277. 3Cf. JOSEPH, op. cit., pp. 377-8. 4 We say "usually," for there are evidences that the popular mind is quite familiar with some applications of the scientific conception itself: for instance, with the procedure at coroners' inquests, and with the convictions of criminals on circum stantial evidence. " The popular idea of the non-reciprocal character of the axiom of causation," writes Professor Welton, " is due to the fact that the ' cause ' is much more frequently analysed than the ' effect ' — using those words in the popular sense of temporal antecedent and consequent phenomena. Thus, when Mill says in support of his doctrine of the Plurality of Causes, ' Many causes may produce death' (op. cit., Bk. III., ch. x., § i), he is obviously speaking very loosely. Death is not the whole effect. Moreover, death can never be death in general, but only some one particular kind of death, and the death caused by a bullet through the heart is not the same kind of death as that due to drowning, and both again differ CONCEPTS OF " REASON " AND « CA USE » 87 between "cause" and "effect," in the popular sense of these terms, is not far to seek : it arises from the practical attitude of people in real life towards causality. When they want to pro duce some one given kind of effect (death, for example), it may matter little to them what particular, individual farm or character this effect may assume, but it will evidently be of the greatest importance for them to have a large number of distinct alter native, individual " causes," or modes of producing the generic effect, to choose from. Hence, while people regard the " effect " in the abstract, contenting themselves with one generic name for it in all its varied individual manifestations, and care little to distinguish between these latter in the concrete, they behave in quite the opposite way towards the " cause " : noting and dis tinguishing carefully, and often naming separately, its various concrete, individual modes or forms, and calling each of these a " The reason," writes Dr. Venn, " why we look out for a cause is not to gratify any feeling of curiosity, at least not primarily, but because we want to produce some particular effect. . . . What the savage mostly wants to do is to produce something or to avert something, not to account for a thing which has already happened. What interests him is to know how to kill somebody, not to know how somebody has been killed. Of course the past must interest him to some extent, because what has happened once may come to pass again, but this is a comparatively indirect or remote reference. What holds good of the savage does so also, though to a somewhat less extent, of the great majority of ordinary people : the explanation of the past will rationally be far sub ordinate in interest to the prediction of the future. . . . When we want to explain a fact an offer of several alternative solutions affords very little help. . . . The scientific student of early culture vexes his mind to ascertain in which of various possible ways fire was first produced, and employed by man ; whether by lightning, by friction of boughs of trees, by sparks from flint chips, or so forth. But for those whose only care was to make a fire when they wanted it, such plurality of causes was all in their favour." 1 And Dr. Mellone thus happily illustrates the same truth : " Sometimes what is practically most important is scientifically least important : it may be of great importance to know what circumstances will produce an event without knowing how they produce it. For instance, it may be of importance to clear from death by poison, and so on. The effect as a totality differs in each case from that in every other case, and the very existence of the enquiries of coroners' in quests is a practical assertion of even popular belief in the reciprocity of the causal relation, as it assumes that by a careful analysis of the total ' effect ' the cause is arrived at, and this assumption can be only justified on the ground that this totality could have had but one cause." — WELTON, op. cit.t pp. 27-8. Cf. JOSEPH, op. cit., pp. 446-47. 1 VENN, Empirical Logic, pp. 56, 63, 64. 88 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC the premises of rats ; traps, strychnine, phosphorus, and terriers are various ' causes ' between which we must choose : but we do not as a rule hold post mortems on dead rats." 1 What Dr. Venn says of the savage and of the ordinary man is also largely true of the scientist : he, too, has a practical as well as a speculative aim in his researches. It is not his sole concern to explain an effect by bringing to light its necessitating and indispensable antecedents, i.e. its reciprocal or commensurate cause : he also wants to discover all the alternative combinations of existing agencies and conditions which embody the indispen sable factors (in inseparable conjunction, perhaps, with many superfluous or indifferent elements) — combinations which con stitute so many practical alternative modes of producing the effect in question. " Properly speaking," writes Mr. Joseph, " to give the cause of anything is to give everything necessary, and nothing superfluous, to its existence. Never theless we should often defeat our ends if we gave precisely this ; if our object in seeking the cause of a thing is that we may be able to produce or prevent it, and if something is necessary to its existence which is a property of an object otherwise superfluous, it would be of no use specifying the property necessary unless we specified the otherwise superfluous object in which it was found." This the author illustrates by remarking : " It may be the texture of the pumice-stone that fits it to remove ink-stains from the skin ; but it would be of more use to tell a man with inky fingers to get a piece of pumice-stone, than to give him a description of the fineness of texture which would render a body capable of making his fingers clean " 3. Similarly, with regard to the " elasticity " of the air (or other elastic medium) as a cause of the transmission of sound : " We want to know what possessed of the necessary elasticity is present when we hear at a distance ; nor could anyone without knowing that prevent the transmission of sound by removing the elastic medium ; for he would not know what to remove ".3 In so far, then, as the scientist has this practical aim before him, he will rest content with discovering " causes " in the wider sense of this term — the sense in which an effect can have a " plurality of causes," i.e. of alternative modes in which it may be produced. Under the influence of this " practical " view of inductive science, Dr. Venn regards this wider conception of cause as " the most serviceable for purposes of inductive logic ".* And in this he is undoubtedly right. But he goes farther, and asserts that the stricter concept of cause — that which makes the causal relation reciprocal — *ofi. cit., p. 275 ; cf. JOSEPH, Logic, p. 446. *ibid., n. 8 ibid, * Empirical Logic, p. 71. CONCEPTS OF "REASON" AND "CAUSE" 89 " necessarily results in rendering it useless for any purposes of inference ". " Make it perfectly complete and accurate," he continues, " and you make it at once hypothetical and the statement of what is to all intents and purposes a mere identity." l [Such an over- refinement of the law of causation] " renders that law suitable only for hypothetical conclusions, in other words, renders it useless for positive inductions about matters of fact ". a Now, it is of course true that if we make our concepts of "cause "and "effect" so comprehensive and closely connected as to involve each other reciprocally, we are not likely to get beyond the hypothetical " If A then C and vice versa" to the categorical "This A will always involve this C and vice versa". It is true, too, that knowledge of the one immediate, indispensable " cause " of C is of less practical utility than knowledge of the numerous alternative groups of antecedents in which this one " cause" is operative. But it is likewise true that if we want a scientific, even though conditional, knowledge of C, a knowledge of how it is produced, we must try to seize the process at the instant of the production of C, and to detect — if we can, or as far as we can — all that is indispensable for its production. In other words, when our aim is not directly practical — like that of the " savage " for instance : to compass a person's death in some way or other — but rather speculative — like that of the coroner, for instance : to discover how this person's death has been compassed — we must obviously seek, not for all the alternative ways in which the person, could have been killed, but for all the factors indispensable to the way in which this particular person has been killed. So, too, when we want to explain a kind of result, we must seek, not for the various modes of producing it in different sets of circumstances, but for that which is common to all the modes, and which, being always "sufficient" and always "indispensable," will produce it in any and every conceivable set of circumstances. For instance, that "kind" of effect called "death" — that which is common to all individal instances of death and in virtue of which we call each of them a " death " — will be scientifically explained by us only when we have succeeded in discovering what precise factor (or group of factors) is present in every conceivable mode of pro ducing " death," as being sufficient and indispensable for its pro duction. A full scientific knowledge — were such attainable — of the relation between a " natural " or " necessary " cause and its effect, would thus show the relation to be reciprocal. One and 1 Empirical Logic, p. 71 (italics ours). 3 ibid., p. 53. 90 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC the same genus of effect (e.g. death) can have only one and the same genus of cause (viz. that generic element which is common to all species of causes of death, making them all alike destructive of life) ; one and the same species of effect (e.g. death from small pox) can have only one and the same species of cause (viz. the microbe of smallpox) ; any one individual effect (e.g. the death of Julius Caesar) can (in its individual totality) have had only one individual (total) cause, viz. that to which it was actually due.1 Now, in the mathematical sciences we establish numerous universal truths which are reciprocal.2 But is it always possible to establish reciprocal causal relations in the inductive sciences? On the contrary, it is rarely possible. Some logicians set it up as an ideal at which the scientist must always aim. He is told to commence his scientific investigations by working with the popular concept of cause, which admits " plurality of causes," and to try to approximate gradually towards the scientific concept which excludes plurality. Dr. Mellone's expression of this theory is clear and accurate. " In the absence of scientific knowledge of the immediate cause, we have to bear in mind that different combinations of circumstances may bring about the same event. Practically we have to begin the investigation by examining those different combinations of circumstances in which the event is produced — considering them, at first, as so many different ' causes '. They are not the immediate cause ; but it is operative in them."* We are to commence, therefore, with the various distinct modes (" causes " in the popular sense) of producing a certain kind of effect, and to finish by abstracting what is common and essential in all of them (the " cause " in the stricter sense). But this ideal is often unattainable, and, if attained, would be often com paratively useless and uninstructive ; and this is so because " the phenomenon under investigation is often highly complex, and subject to all sorts of varia tion on the different occasions of its occurrence, through variations in the 1 Cf. JOSEPH, op cit., p. 65 : " Whenever science tries to find the cause not of a particular event, such as the French Revolution (whose cause must be as unique as that event itself is), but of an event of a kind, such as consumption, or com mercial crises, it looks in the last resort for a commensurate cause. What is that exact state or condition of the body, given which it must and without which it can not be in a consumption ? What are those conditions in a commercial community, given which there must and without which there cannot be a commercial crisis ? " The same is true, of course, in regard to the cause of a " particular event " — except that this is regarded as belonging to the domain of history, not of science, which is " of the universal ". 3 Cf. JOSEPH, op. cit., pp. 443, supra, 212. 3 MIJLLONE, op. cit., p. 277. CONCEPTS OF "REASON" AND "CAUSE" 91 objects or events contributing to its production ; not the whole nature of the objects or events under whose influence it occurs is relevant to its occurrence, but only certain particular properties or modes of action ; and it is possible to formulate severally the principles of action involved, from which the joint result may be seen to follow, where it would not be possible to assign to the phenomenon any group of concrete objects or events as cause, about which we could say not only that, given them the phenomenon must be given, but also that, given the phenomenon, they must have been given too " *. . . " For example, we may ask what is the cause of the monsoons — that is, of the regular and periodic winds that blow steadily in certain regions for one part of the year and for another in the opposite direction ? If we said that they were due to periodic alterations in the distribution of atmospheric pressure, it would not be very instructive ; for we really want to know what events happening in those regions, produce these differences. Yet the events which contribute to determine the deviation and direction of the monsoons are numerous and variable. . . ." 2 And these numerous and variable events are due to the variously combined influences and activities of sun and sea and land and air and aqueous vapour— among other things. Now, in such a case as this, to seek for the reciprocating or indispensable " cause " of the monsoon would be futile. " To give the cause of monsoons, without deficiency or superfluity, would mean that we must not mention the sun (because only the heat of its rays is material), nor the sea (because only its fluidity and its power of giving off vapour concern us, and a lake, if it was big enough, would do as well), nor any other of the concrete things which act in the way required, but only their requisite actions." 8 But no one would dream of giving the cause of the monsoons without mentioning those various agencies ; and in giving them " we shall have to include in our statement of the cause elements at least theoretically superfluous ". Shall we, then, rest content with a bare enumeration of these partly superfluous agencies ; simply stating, in explana tion of the monsoons, that these are due to the combined influences of sun and air and land and sea ? No ; something more than this is expected, even though an exact statement of the " commensurate cause " is not expected. There is a middle course, a third alternative, which is expected, and it is this : that we " look for the principles in accordance with which [these] objects [or agencies] act under certain circumstances ; then we can show that the mon soon is only the complex result of the action of a number of objects under the particular circumstances of the case, and in accordance with the principles of action which our ' laws ' express " 4. In other words, " we alter the form of our problem. Looking upon the phenomenon as the complex result of many conditions, we attempt to determine not [merely] what assemblage of objects or events will produce the result, nor [again, attempt to determine] on what properties or events therein it depends [the reciprocating cause] ; but what is the principle of action in \the~\ different objects or events, in virtue of which some one particular condition necessary to the production of the phenomenon is realized in them. For the reciprocating cause of a complex phenomenon we substitute as the object of our search the principle in accord- 1 JOSEPH, op. cit., pp. 445, 446 (italics ours). 3 ibid., p. 444. 3 ibid., p. 445. 4 ibid, (italics ours). 92 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC ance with which a certain kind of object or event acts. Our problem is better expressed as that of discovering laws of nature than causes" J In explanation of the monsoons, for instance, we are expected " to point out the difference in the power of the sun at any place produced by the varying directness of its rays ; how the sea gives off vapour ; how vapour absorbs part of the heat of the sun's rays ; how the heated water circulates with the colder ; how the earth absorbs and retains the heat of the sun ; how air is expanded by heat ; how the principle of atmospheric pressure acts under conditions of different expansion ; and so forth. Then we can see that if a cer tain combination of events occurs, a particular complex result must arise ; if the sun travels from over the surface of the sea to over the interior of a continent, we shall find monsoons ; for the difference between summer and winter temperature will in the interior be very great, but on the sea, owing to the way in which the moisture of the air absorbs part of the heat, and the currents in the water carry away part, it is not so great ; hence as summer is ending, the air inland will be hotter and have expanded more than out at sea, as winter is ending, it will be colder and have contracted more ; so that at one time the current of air sets inland in accordance with the laws of atmospheric pressure, and at another time it sets shoreward ".a Here we have an admirable example of the explanation of a complex effect by stating the laws according to which the various contributing agents act in such conjunctions as to bring about this effect. It is not the " laws " or their combinations that produce the effect ; it is the various " causes " or " agents " that produce the effect, by acting each according to its own uniform " principle of action," that is, according to the " law " of its nature (217). These "laws" are both descriptive and explanatory: de scriptive of the modes of action of the causes, and explanatory of the effects by showing how these latter are brought about by those causes (255). JOSEPH, Logic, chaps. xix.,xxii. WELTON, op. cit. ii., pp. 1-60. VENN, Empirical Logic, chaps, i., ii., iii. MERCIER, Logique, pp. 298-332. MEL- LONE, op. cit., pp. 264 sqq. JOYCE, Logic, chaps, xv., xviii. MILL, Logic, 1 JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 444 (italics ours). *ibid., pp. 444-5. CHAPTER IV. PRESUPPOSITIONS OF INDUCTION: UNIFORMITY OF NATURE. 223. INTERPRETATIONS OF THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN NATURE. — In the preceding chapter attention was called to two principles presupposed by induction : " sufficient reason " and "causality". There is another principle which it postulates still more directly and explicitly, the Uniformity of Nature. The aim of induction being to reach — as far as may be — general truths or laws about certain domains of our experience, it does and must assume in a special way that the agencies which it studies be uni form in their modes of operation throughout space and time. Only in so far forth as these agencies act regularly, uniformly, will our generalizations about them be reliable. About what is variable, unstable, capricious, we can make no certain or scientific general statement.1 We can have science only of what is orderly and amenable to law. Therefore, underlying the inductive process by which we establish general laws of nature, there is the postulate known as the uniformity of nature. It has been stated in many alternative ways by logicians, philosophers, and scientists, the most usual formula, perhaps, being this one : " The same physical causes, acting in similar circumstances, produce similar results ".2 There has also been much discussion about its precise import and rela tion to induction, about the origin of our belief in it, and the grounds on which we yield it our assent. Before examining these questions, a word about the sphere of application of the principle may not be out of place. Strictly 1c/. JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 374. 2 Compare the formula of Duns Scotus : " Whatever has resulted regularly and constantly from the action of a non-free cause cannot be due to chance, but must be connected with the nature of that cause, and will therefore always result from it " (supra, 208). Other alternative statements are : " Nature is uniform in its mode of action " ; " the future will resemble the past " ; " the unobserved will resemble the ob served" ; " the unknown will resemble the known " (cf. VENN, op. cit., pp. 119 sqq.). 93 94 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC speaking, it applies only to the action of non-free or necessitating causes; these we call "physical" or "natural" causes in the present context, as distinct from the free, self-determining activity of the human will. The action of the former produces physical uniformity, that of the latter only uniformity in the wider sense — moral uniformity. But it would be a mistake to imagine that this looser and less reliable sort of uniformity, which characterizes the phenomena dependent on human activity, is an insufficient groundwork for scientific knowledge of these domains : the very existence of the various social and economic sciences, their co existence with human free-will, disproves any such assumption.1 About the generalizations of the latter sciences we can, of course, have only moral certitude, not physical ; and it is to non-free causes, and to the law of physical uniformity, that we must mainly direct our attention here. Is the law of uniformity, as understood to apply to the action of non-free causes, an axiomatic, setf-evident, necessary, " analytic " principle — like the principle of causality, for example, that " what ever happens has a cause " ? Or is it rather a derived, " synthetic," mediately evident truth, to which we assent only on grounds of experience ? Some have held the former, some the latter view. As a matter of fact the principle can be, and has been, interpreted in two ways. Understood as a hypothetical judgment, it is a self- evident, axiomatic truth ; regarded as categorical, it is a truth of experience. The hypothetical judgment, " If, or whenever, or wherever, the same physical (non-free) cause acts in similar circumstances (and therefore unimpeded, not interfered with by other causes), it will always produce the same sort of effect," — is an axiomatic, analytic, self-evident judgment. For, as Father Joyce expresses it, " the very concept of a natural agent, devoid of free-will, in volves that, under the same circumstances, its action will be of the same kind ".2 It is a judgment whose truth the mind grasps directly and intuitively from an adequate understanding of the notions involved in it: "physical, non-free cause," "repeated action unimpeded," " similarity of effect ". But the principle, thus stated, makes no categorical assertion 1 Cf. MAKER, Psychology, 4th edition, pp. 423-4. Mr. JOSEPH (op. cit., t . 375) seems to identify man's free actions, with capricious, motiveless actions, and to regard them as, therefore, " incalculable ". But this is not an accurate conception of the " libertarian " view of the will. C/. MAKER, op. cit.t pp. 396 sqq. 9 Principles of Logic, p. 237. UNIFORMITY OF NATURE 95 about any individual case. It " supposes the First Cause to preserve the ordinary operation of natural laws".1 This supposition is expli citly contained in the reference to "similar circumstances". A case of interference by the First Cause would alter the circum stances. Such a case would not come under the principle. As stated, therefore, the principle is a metaphysically necessary one. It is, moreover, self-evident to anyone who understands the import of the concepts involved in it. These, however, are com plex concepts, and to acquire them is a work of time and experi ence ; for which reason we may admit that the principle, even understood hypothetically, is, to use the words of Mill,2 " by no means one of the earliest which any of us ... can have" reached. It is a propositio per se nota in se (86). That is, it is an analytic, a priori proposition, whose truth is grasped intuitively by the mind as soon as the concepts involved in it are fully analysed and juxtaposed in thought. But we may freely admit that it is not a propositio per se nota quoad omnes, that it is not — like " two and two are four " — immediately evident to everybody, because not everybody has clear and definite notions about the nature of a physical or non-free cause, its activity in similar conditions, and uniformity of effect. We need to become familiar with the ordinary operations of nature in order to conceive the notion of natural cause, i.e. of a cause which is not free to determine itself- — as the human will does — to produce this, that, or the other effect : a cause which has one definite, fixed line of action, one stable tendency which it endea vours as it were to realize and satisfy by its action. But, as soon as a person has formed, from his experience of the uniform re currence of natural phenomena, the idea of a "physical or natural cause or agent, acLing repeatedly in similar sets of circumstances" he will see intuitively, by an analysis of that concept, and comparison with the concept of "uniform production of the same effect" a metaphysically necessary connexion between them. The principle of uniformity, understood in this hypothetical or formal sense, is, however, nothing more than a purely formal generalization of an abstract judgment, which prescinds from the actual existence or occurrence of any such entity as a "physical or non-free cause ". It does not imply that there are such causes in existence, nor that they act repeatedly in similar circumstances, 1 JOYCE, op. cit., p. 238. 2 Logic, III., xxi., 2. 96 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC but merely states that " If such causes do exist and act thus, they will always produce the same classes of effects " It may, perhaps, be objected that we could not have formed the notion of "non-free causes " at all, unless there were such causes in the world revealed to us by our senses. This, however, is scarcely so. The data of our sense knowledge must, of course, have presented such uniformity as suggested the idea of "non- free " causes to us. But we might conceivably have been mis taken in adopting that suggestion, and judging that the causes of those phenomena are really non-free : just as those philosophers who deny free-will maintain that we are really mistaken in con cluding from the facts of our own internal experience that we have free-will. However this may be, the hypothetical statement of the principle of uniformity evades this question of fact in regard to non-free causes. The categorical statement of the same principle, however, implies and asserts the fact of their actual existence. It is not, therefore, in the formal generalization of the abstract principle — in the assertion that " If '(whenever ; wherever, as often as) any physical cause acts in the same circumstances, it will pro duce similar effects " — that the difficulty lies, but in its material generalization, i.e., (a) in asserting that there are and have been and will be such causes in existence, and (b] in proving that the various cases which we allege to be actual instances illustrative of the principle are indeed such.1 In order, for instance, to be able to apply the abstract principle of uniformity in (a) establishing by induction the general law that "an iron bar is lengthened by the application of heat," 2 and in (ft) applying this law to any particular case, we must be able not merely to assert the. formally general (hypothetical) principle that " natural or non-free causes produce the same results if they act repeatedly in similar circumstances," but we must be able further more to assert categorically (a) that heat acting on iron is such a cause, and will therefore always lengthen an iron bar, and (£) that this particular case is really a case of an iron bar acted on by heat. The general categorical assertion, that " the causes which are at work in the physical universe are non-free, or fixed by nature in their mode of action, and that therefore they always have acted'and always lcf. MER«IER, Logique, p. 330. 2 We assume here, with Mill, whatever about the conventions of formal logic, that all such physical laws and general truths, reached by experience, imply the exist ence or occurrence of the things and events to which they refer (cf. 128). UNIFORMITY OF NATURE 97 will act uniformly" goes distinctly farther than the hypothetical principle that " if a cause is faced necessarily to one mode of action it will act uniformly in similar circumstances". Yet those two distinct and separate statements are sometimes identified, or rather confounded, under the common designation of the " uniformity ot nature ". And those who rightly distinguish between them usually limit the latter title to the abstract, hypothetical principle, describing the categorical assertion as belief1 " in the maintenance of the present order of things in the universe ". Thus Dr. Mellone, in his Introductory Text-Book of Logic? draws "an important dis tinction between two meanings of the uniformity of nature: (i) the uniformity of causation, (2) the maintenance of the present order of things in the universe. Experience [he continues] shows us that there are general 'laws' — i.e. kinds of orderly succes sion in the outward course of events : such as appear in the suc cession of day and night, summer and winter, seed-time and harvest, life and death. The regular succession of events in a thousand different ways accustoms us, from force of habit, to ex pect things to happen in a regular order ; and we find that the expectation is fulfilled. This constitutes an overwhelming pre sumption in favour of the maintenance of the present arrangements in nature ; but it does not show that derivations from this order are impossible. An expectation, bred by experience and custom, that events will occur in a certain way is not the same as a know ledge that they must so occur ; and this knowledge is not in our possession. We have no grounds for affirming that the sun must rise to-morrow morning ; there is only an overwhelming presump tion in favour of the expectation that it will. But the principle of uniform causation tells us nothing as to the permanence of the present ' choir of heaven and furniture of earth '. It only says that the same cause will have the same effect ; and to this there are no exceptions. The same cause may conceivably never act again ; but this does not affect the truth of the principle that if it did it would have the same effect ". But, then, is the inductive process, by which we establish a law of physical nature ("IfS is M it is P" : "Ifa bar of iron be heated it will be elongated"}, an application merely of the 1 This " belief" extends to the past no less than to the future, to the distant as well as to the near ; it is a conviction which has for its object the existence and opera tion, throughout time and space, of natural or necessitating causes, 2 pp. 281-2. VOL. II. 7 98 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC hypothetical "principle," or does it also involve the categorical "belief"? The answer is that if the laws of physical nature are anything more than statements of mere abstract possibilities ; if they are taken to imply the actual existence and operation, throughout space and time, of the agencies they refer to, then the inductive process by which we reach them does undoubtedly imply not only the hypothetical principle, but also the categorical belief. And that physical laws are interpreted in this latter sense, as informing us not about mere abstract possibilities, but about concrete actualities, past, present, and future, there can be no doubt. In reference to such a law, for example, as " Heating (M~} an iron bar (S) causes its elongation (P] ". Dr. Mellone * says that " the connexion between M and P is independent of time and place. We can reason backwards to unobserved cases in the past, and dip into the future and be sure that P will always be produced by M". But how sure can we be about this latter? No surer than we can be that heat and iron (M and S} will continue to exist ; for unless they continue to exist, the operation can never take place. And what certitude have we that they will continue to exist? The physical, hypothetical certitude which Dr. Mellone describes as an " overwhelming presumption ". In fact, we can not extend or apply a single physical law to a single future case — or to a single past or distant case for that matter, if it lies out side our actual experience — without assuming (a) that the causes it refers to are "necessary," "natural," or "non-free" causes, and (b] that they have acted, are acting, or will act, in the case contemplated, without any obstacle or impediment from the inter vention of other causes. Similarly, Father Joyce'2 seems to take the "principle of uniformity " as embodying not merely the abstract judgment that "anon-free cause acts uniformly in similar circumstances," but also the judgment that " such causes do exist and act in the universe," when he says that " in that principle we have the guarantee that our universal judgment will be verified in fact. Our judgment that A as such is the cause of a, would help us but little, unless we further knew that in the real order the same cause does actually always produce the same effect." This being the sense in which Mill understood the principle, it 1 op. cit., p. 265. *op. cit., p. 219. UNIFORMITY OF NATURE 99 is no wonder that he regarded it as synthetic, as reached by experience, not as analytic and self-evident like the mere hypo thetical statement of uniformity. If, therefore, the principle of uniformity be understood to assert categorically our belief in the actual existence and operation, throughout space and time, of non-free causes, we have to determine (i) what are the ultimate rational grounds on which we assent to this principle, and (2) what are its relations to the processes of induction and deduction respectively. 224. ULTIMATE RATIONAL GROUNDS OF OUR BELIEF IN UNIFORMITY: THE SCHOLASTIC, EMPIRICIST, AND IDEALIST VIEWS. — Firstly, as to the rational grounds of our assent to the principle. We must bear in mind that it is a synthetic, or a posteriori generalization from experience, about which we have physical certitude.1 Our concept of physical or non-free cause is not innate. We form it gradually from our acquaintance with uniformity in the processes of physical nature. From our ex perience of the uniform activities of the physical universe we abstract the notion of a necessary or non-free cause, fixed in its mode of action : just as from our internal experience of our own activity, and from observation of the activities of men in general, we abstract the notion of a free or self -deter mining cause, not fixed to one mode of acting in similar circumstances. Hav ing, then, defined for ourselves a non-free or physical cause as " one which will always act the same way, by a necessity of its nature or constitution, in similar circumstances," we deli berately judge that the causes of which we have experience in physical nature verify our definition : we judge that they will always act the same way in similar circumstances, in the future as in the past, provided something unwonted, extraordinary, unfore seen, does not occur. Thus, while we quite recognize that at least apparent exceptions to uniformity have occurred in the past, that our knowledge of the forces of nature is limited, that some of its phenomena " seem altogether capricious," 2 that unknown agencies, not calculated by us, may have interfered, and may again interfere, and surprise us by upsetting our expectations: nevertheless, we consider it prudent and reasonable to base upon 1 C/. MAHER, Psychology (4th edition), p. 420: "The latter generalization [that the ' laws of nature are constant '] is a contingent truth which we can easily con ceive subject to exceptions ". a MILL, op. clt.t III., iii., § 2. zoo THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC our actual experience of general uniformity, imperfect and pos sibly interrupted though this may be, a firm belief or expectation that the same regularity which has obtained within the limits of our actual experience will obtain also outside these limits. Thus, actual experience of uniformity may be regarded as the proximate, psychical ground of our belief in uniformity beyond this experience. But we must go further if we are to assign an ultimate rational justification for this belief. If I am asked why I believe that nature is uniform beyond the actual range of my own personal sense experience, it will not suffice to answer : " Because I have found it uniform within this range ". No doubt, this is the true psychological account of the genesis of my ex pectation that the uniformity will obtain beyond my experience ; and, no doubt, I may quite prudently and reasonably act upon this belief. I may go on investigating nature as a scientist, observing, experimenting, conjecturing general truths or laws, generalizing from experience, and in this way passing beyond experience, even discovering and establishing laws of physical nature : I may do all this without once pausing to inquire what rational grounds I have at any time for going a single step beyond my actual experience of nature and inferring anything with any rational certitude about what is beyond this experience. But what right have I to infer that because a thing has existed, or an event happened, in a certain uniform way within my very limited experience, it therefore does, or will, or must exist, or happen, in the same way beyond ? What right had Leibniz to think or say that " 'Tis all like here . . . The present is preg nant with the future ; the future may be deciphered in the past. . . . The distant is mirrored in the near"?1 The "leap" beyond experience takes place in every single induction we make, because we believe in the " uniformity of nature ". But what right have we to believe in it? What view of nature will afford us a rational justification of this belief? Scholastic View. — Philosophers differ in assigning an ulti mate rational ground for our belief in the uniformity of nature, because they differ in their views about the ultimate nature of the universe itself. The justification Scholastics offer — in common with all who admit creation, and the dependence of all nature on 1 " C'est tout comme ici. . . . Le present est gros de 1'avenir ; le futur se pour- rait lire dans le passe . . . l'e"loigne est exprim^ par le prochain." — apud VENN, Empirical Logic, p. 81 ; cf. 124. UNI FORM IT Y OF NA TURE i o i the Providence of an All-wise Deity1 — is simple and intelligible. By reasoning from effect to cause, by means of a posteriori argu ments whereby we apply self-evident principles, like the principle of causality, to the facts of sense experience, we establish with certitude the existence of an All-powerful, All-wise, Supreme Being, who has freely created the universe, freely conserves it in existence, and freely concurs with the activity of all created agencies ; who has manifestly ordered and arranged and designed the universe, the " cosmos " as it is rightly called ; who has evidently endowed the agencies of this visible universe with^Jra/ tendencies, in virtue of which they act uniformly unless whenever or wherever He chooses to interfere (miraculously) with the established physical order for some higher (moraF) end. Know ing all this, we know that natural causes will continue to exist and to act uniformly in accordance with His will and as long as He wills. Knowing, too, that He is All-wise, we know and believe that He will not interfere with the uniformity of physical nature capriciously, so as to render our reliance on it uncertain. Since He created its agencies "for man's use and benefit," this Divine purpose forms a firm basis for our trust in their stability. His occasional miraculous suspensions of its laws are for our greater good, and cannot in any way weaken our belief in its general uniformity (cf. 2 1 7). Thus it is that our conception of physical nature as the work of an All-wise Creator and Ruler, forms the ultimate rational justification of that belief in the uniformity of nature, which is partially embodied in the formulation and application of every physical law. This, of course, does not mean that we must have deliberately convinced ourselves of God's existence, creation, and providence, before we can make a single inductive generalization from actual experience in any department of natural research : we may assume the uniformity of nature provisionally, and utilize our postulate as scientists, without justifying to ourselves the use we make of it. But if we want to justify this usage philosophically ; we must, of course, put some rational interpretation on both nature and thought — i.e. on our experience as a whole. 1 The Scottish school of philosophers are content to say that this belief is the natural expression of an innate, instinctive law. There is no denying the natural tendency to the belief; but to say that the latter must be " the effect of instinct, not of reason," is hardly to explain it. The tendency to the belief should not be called an "instinct"; for, although its exercise is spontaneous and unreflective, still, on reflection, we can assign a rational basis for it. 102 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC The existence of God can be proved independently of the assumption that nature is uniform in the sense in which this uni formity has just been explained.1 Hence, the Scholastic justifica tion of the postulate is free from all circular reasoning, in addition to being intelligible and adequate. But perhaps this fallacy is involved in applying belief in uniformity to individual inductive generalizations before we have -explicitly assigned to this belief its ultimate rational basis ? No, because every such generalization is merely provisional : the assumption of uniformity invblved in it awaits whatever rational justification we may be able to supply for this assumption when we reflect upon it. Empiricist View. — Mill was right, as we have seen above, in saying that belief in the general uniformity of nature (in the categorical sense) is " by no means one of the earliest " 2 of our beliefs : it is not a mental assent which must precede every scien tific induction we make : it is partially embodied in each, and gradually extended over all nature.3 But he failed utterly to assign any ground for rational, scientific certitude, whether about this widest law of uniformity of nature, or about any minor generalization reached by induction. He sought to show that the minor generalizations we make without explicit advertence or assent to the general uniformity of nature, can be only mere enumerative inductions, i.e. more or less hazardous extensions of observed uniformities to the region beyond our actual experience ; that our belief in the general uniformity of nature is a gradual summing up of these hazardous conclusions ; and that, neverthe less, this summing-up process gives us the highest attainable scien tific certitude about this law of uniformity, this widest of all generalizations. The general uniformity of nature is, he teaches, a generalization from a number of less general uniformities, them selves reached by a " loose and uncertain mode of induction per enumerationem simplicem ". The law of the uniformity of nature " is itself an instance of induction, and by no means one of the earliest which any of us, or which mankind in general, can have 1 The same observed and experienced uniformity which prompts us to act on the assumption of its universality, also furnishes, of course, part of the data from which the existence of God is demonstrated. But in using the data for this purpose we are not assuming the principle of uniformity. 2 Logic, III., xxi., § 2. 3 Cf. infra, 225 ; VENN, op. cit., pp. 134 sqq. For the opposite view— that belief in, or assumption of, general uniformity — is necessarily antecedent to any and every inductive generalization, see JOSEPH, op. cit., pp. 386 sqq. UNI FORM IT Y OF NA TURE 1 03 made. We arrive at this universal law by generalization from many laws of inferior generality. . . . As, however, all rigorous processes of induction presuppose the general uniformity, our knowledge of the particular uniformities from which it was first inferred was not, of course, derived from rigorous induction, but from the loose and uncertain mode of induction/^ enumerationem simplicem" * And of this latter process he had already said : "It consists in ascribing the character of general truths to all propositions which are true in every instance that we happen to know of. ... In science it carries us but a little way. We are forced to begin with it ; we must often rely on it provisionally, in the absence of means of more searching investigation." 2 There is here, ap parently, no rational basis assigned, on which this " loose" process can produce scientific certitude. Yet, it is by this process we ascend to the " particular uniformities," and, by a second applica tion of it, from these to the " general uniformity," on which the validity of the whole inductive process is to be based. The principle so obtained must necessarily be, as Professor Welton expresses it, " untrustworthy in a twofold degree ; for it is an in ference, uncertain in its very essence, from other inferences of the same dubious character. . . . Mill's argument on this point is indeed nothing but a petitio pn 'ncipii. We are, he says, ' to con sider no minor generalization as proved except in so far as the law of causation confirms it ' (III., xxi., § 3), and yet that law is to be derived from those very same minor generalizations which it is called upon to ' confirm'." 3 Mill is, of course, mistaken in thinking that we cannot make a strict, scientific induction without hav'mg previously justified our belief in the general uniformity of nature. We have pointed out above that this is not necessary ; that we may accept the principle provisionally and base our scientific inductions upon it. Mill, however, thinks we can only make " enumerative " inductions ; and upon these alone he endeavours to base our belief in that general uniformity, which will then turn around and confirm them. His attempt to avoid the charge of inconsistency in basing the validity of the " rigorous " process upon the " loose and un certain " process, reveals once more a rather naive petitio prindpii. The difficulty he had to face was this : Enumerative induction, 1 Logic, III., xxi., § 2. 2 ibid., iii., § 2. 3 WELTON, Logic, ii., pp. 42, 43. C/~. JOSEPH, op. cit., pp. 388, 391. 104 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC i.e. generalizing from the mere counting of instances, is admittedly a hazardous process and cannot give certitude. How, then, can we be certain of the uniformity of nature, and through it, of our scientific inductions, if uniformity itself is grounded on this hazardous process of enumeration ? Mill commences his answer1 with this statement : " Now, the precariousness of the method of simple enumeration is in an inverse ratio to the largeness of the generalization ". Assuming this, he points out that the subject- matter of the law of uniformity — which is the " largest " general ization of all — is " so widely diffused that there is no time, no place, and no combination of circumstances, but must afford an example of its truth or of its falsity," and that it was "never found otherwise than true ".2 From this he concludes that the law of uniformity " takes its place among the most firmly estab lished as well as the largest truths accessible to science ". This is a plausible piece of reasoning until we advert to the fact that its opening statement assumes what is to be proved. The reason why we regard a wide enumerative induction as safer than a narrow one, the reason why one which is found to range without exception over an extensive region of time and space yields higher certitude, is because we are made morally certain by it that the special observed uniformity in question is not a casual but a causal one, and because we ARE ALREADY CONVINCED, or ALREADY ASSUME, that a CAUSAL uniformity will persist beyond and outside our experience, in other words, THAT NATURE IS UNIFORM. Did we not already believe in the uniformity of nature, all enumera tive induction, whether wide or narrow, in fact all inference be yond actual experience, would be equally hazardous. To assume that we can thus differentiate between wide and narrow inductions, in an attempt to prove that we can believe nature to be uniform, is simply to beg the question at issue. Mill's attempt, therefore, to assign a rational basis for belief in the uniformity of nature breaks down. And hence he is unable to justify the individual scientific inductions by which we establish isolated laws of nature ; for in every one of these inductions there is a partial application of the principle of uniformity ; every one of them transcended the actual sense experience of the individual ; 1 Logic, III., xxi., § 3. 2 What about his previous recognition [III., iii., § 2] of phenomena, which " seem altogether capricious," about the " course of nature" being " not only uniform" but "also infinitely various"? Again, what about miracles? Or about the impossi bility of inferring what must be, or even what will be, merely from what was or is ? UNIFORMITY OF NATURE 105 every one of them " did most certainly outreach the boundaries of observation as then and there obtained " ; l and in the Empiri cist philosophy, which reduces all knowledge to sense experience, there is nothing to justify a single step beyond the present data of the individual's sense consciousness. This philosophy recog nizes no channel of knowledge beyond the senses, and reduces all nature, all reality, to a mere flow of conscious sensations in the individual mind. The step, therefore, beyond what is actually observed — in fact, the step beyond the contents of the present transient moment of consciousness — is, for the phenomenist, at best a presumption, a "hazard," a "leap,"2 a speculation, about the validity of which we may have a more or less strong expecta tion, hope, opinion, probability ; but not certitude proper : at least, not a scientific or reasoned certitude, for which any sufficient rational grounds can be assigned (cf. 2 1 9). Idealist View. — In the sensist philosophy there is room for knowledge of individual ^a^/ or phenomenon alone ; for law, neces sity, the universal, there is no logical place. In the Scholastic doctrine, that the universe is dependent on the free-will of an All-wise Creator and Ruler, there is an intelligible place for physical or conditional certitude about the nature, activities, and laws of physical agencies, conceived as subject to the will and wisdom of that Creator. The idealist philosophy errs in, the op posite extreme from sensism by attributing to the processes of external nature an absolute, metaphysical necessity to which they can have no real claim. The advocates of this philosophy — to which we have already called attention (cf. 215) — prefer to speak of the unity of nature, rather than its uniformity. They tell us that " the world must be conceived as a systematic totality, with a thoroughgoing interrelation of parts . . . that nature is a unity ... a system which remains identical with itself amidst the unceasing changes of relations between its parts, and which, by its own nature, necessitates and determines those changes ".3 And they assert this " unity " as a postulate or " presupposition," without which intelligible experience would be impossible.4 Now it is true, undoubtedly, that unless the world were a harmonious system of interrelated elements, regular, uniform, con sistent with itself throughout all its changes, we could not arrive 1 VENN, Empirical Logic, p. 131. 2 BAIN, Inductive Logic, book iii., chap, i., § i. 3 WELTON, Logic, ii., pp. 4, 5. 4 ibid. io6 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC at a rational knowledge of it ; for knowing implies defining, ar ranging, and classifying things ; and the validity of these processes obviously depends on the condition that their objects have abiding, permanent natures. Whatever is knowable, therefore, is reducible to order within a system. But in this sense the unity implied in reality is of course unity of order, unity by relation, not unity of being or essence, as these philosophers would seem to imply. This pantheistic postulate will not stand the test of critical analysis. In the real world, as revealed to us through our senses, we detect a unity of order, but not a unity of being ; we see in it manifold evidences which justify us in inferring that it is created, conserved, and ruled by some guiding intelligence distinct from it ; but we do not by any means see in it only such logically necessary con nexions and relations as would justify us in believing it to be a mere manifestation or evolution of the activity of some immanent intellect. We can prove that the " choir of heaven and furniture of earth " are dependent on Divine providence, on the wisdom and free-will of the Deity, and we can therefore be physically, hypothetically certain of the generalizations we reach by means of induction about the modes of existence and activity of agencies created in time and space ; but absolute or metaphysical certitude about these modes of existence and activity, the very nature of these agencies, and the essential limitations of the human mind itself, preclude us from ever reaching. Modern logicians may, perhaps, be tempted to deprecate the introduction, into a treatise on logic,1 of such metaphysical theses as that God has created and conserves and governs the universe and concurs with its activities, and that man is endowed with free-will, for the purpose of explaining the nature and grounds of physical and moral certitude. But the fact is that these latter cannot be satisfactorily explained, either in logic or outside it, with out adopting some attitude or other as to the ultimate nature, origin, and mode of existence, of this visible univei'se which furnishes the human mind with all its data for knowledge. Metaphysical assumptions of some kind are inevit able in logic, even although it is in metaphysics and not in logic that they should be justified. If John Stuart Mill introduces into his logic, as he does, the assumption of the empiricist or phenomenist philosophy, that all reality is ultimately analysable into spontaneously associated sensations of the conscious mind, and if Professors Bosanquet and Welton build their logical doctrine on the idealist assumption of Hegel and Green, which identifies reality with thought by declaring the former to be constituted by " thought-relations," Scholastics need not apologize for rejecting both the one and the other assump tion as unsatisfactory and erroneous, for attributing a larger role to intellect 1 cf. JOYCE, Logic, pp. 237-8 ; RICKABV, First Principles, pp. 89, 93, 102. UNIFORMITY OF NATURE 107 than the Empiricists, and a larger role to sense than the Idealists, for replacing the Agnosticism of the former, and the Pantheism or Monism of the latter, by the philosophy of Christian Theism, which teaches that the world was created by an All-wise Deity, and is conserved and governed by His power and provi dence. Writers in sympathy with a spiritualist or idealist interpretation of experi ence have furnished very destructive criticisms of Empiricism. But their own substitutes are often far from satisfactory. We may instance the account of uniformity given by Mr. Joseph.1 He deals with the principle as interpreted in the categorical sense, i.e. as believed by us to be de facto applicable to the universe revealed to us in sense experience. He shows clearly and conclu sively that it cannot be established by induction in the manner propounded by Mill.2 His own view is that uniformity is a postulate, an assumption which must be made antecedently to all induction : " all induction assumes the existence of universal connexions in nature ".;t He points out also, and rightly, that belief in the uniformity of the causal relation really involves belief in its necessary character, belief that it is a law* But he goes on to draw a dis tinction between " conditional " and " unconditional " laws or principles. A "conditional" principle he defines as one whose truth "depends upon con ditions which are not stated in if";5 such a principle, therefore, may "admit of exception " B when any of those unmentioned conditions are not verified. An "unconditional" principle is, of course, one which is true absolutely and unconditionally, one " that can have no exception ".7 The uniformity of nature he apparently holds to be an unconditional principle or law, for he says it " involves the truth, without exception or qualification, of all unconditional laws ".s Let us see, then, how he attempts to show that it is unconditional. For, if the principle of uniform causation is unconditional, it undoubtedly "becomes . . . important to determine, if possible, when we have discovered an unconditional law".9 He gives us two tests, one admittedly satisfactory ; the other admittedly less so. Theyfrr/ is simply cogent self-evidence : "if a principle is self-evident it must be unconditional ".10 Such truths, therefore, as "two and two are four," "ex nihilo nihil fit" "a thing must be itself," etc. are unconditional because self-evident. So, too, is the abstract, hypothetical statement of uniformity — "if natural causes have fixed, stable modes of acting . . . they will produce similar effects in similar circumstances " — " un conditional " because it is " self-evident ". But is the categorical statement, that "nature actually is and must be uniform," a self-evident proposition? It certainly is not.11 I op. cit., c. xix. 2 pp. 387-389. 3 p. 371. 4 pp. 376 3qq. 5p. 381. «p. 386. 7p. 382. 8p. 381. 9 p. 382. 10 p. 386 ; cf. p. 384. II We cannot claim the categorical principle to be self-evident unless we claim that the application of our abstract, universal concepts (and of the evidently necessary and universal abstract truths which the mind enunciates by comparing these con cepts with one another) to the concrete data of our sense experience (for the inter pretation of these latter), is an evidently valid process ; in other words, unless we claim that the doctrine of Realism in regard to the significance of our intellectual concepts is, in some form or other, an evidently true doctrine : an indefensible claim, because some forms of realism are not true, and the true form is not evident. Yet, io8 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC Let us therefore apply to it the second test, which is this : " if without assuming [the principle] to be true, it is impossible to account for the facts of our experience, we should have to suppose it unconditional ; though such im possibility may be hard to establish "^ The law of uniform causation is supposed to fulfil this test, to be the only principle on which we can " account for the facts of our experience," and, therefore, to be unconditionally true. And this supposed impossibility of otherwise accounting for "the facts of our experience " is also alleged as the ultimate ground and justification of our belief in the law : " With what right then do we assume it ? The answer to this has been given in discussing what we mean by it. To deny it is to resolve the universe into items that have no intelligible connexion ".2 This whole position calls for a few considerations. Firstly, to prove in this indirect way that a principle must be true — because, namely, it is the only one that will "account for the facts of our experience" — is a perfectly legitimate procedure when the principle is not self-evident. It is a difficult method, of course, to apply ; but, failing self-evidence, it is the only one ; nor do we see why, having applied it carefully, " we should not be fully satisfied with it,"3 as Mr. Joseph thinks we should not. Is he himself, then, not fully satisfied with the only way in which the law of uniform causation in its categorical or applied sense can be shown to be true ? Secondly, if the law is established in this way, is it not based on facts, and established by experience, as we have contended that it is ? * It is assumed although Mr. Joseph nowhere states that the law of (uniform) causation (in the cate gorical or applied sense) is self-evident, he does assert that our belief in it " rests . . . on the perception that a thing must be itself. If it is the nature of one thing to produce change in another, it will always produce that change in that other thing; just as, if it is the nature of a triangle to be half the area of the rectangle on the same base and between the same parallels, it will always be half that area" (op. cit., p. 390 n.). But, manifestly, the parity between those two examples holds good only on an assumption which is, to put it mildly, not self-evident : the assumption that the same necessity which characterizes the relations between static, abstract thought- objects, or possible essences, in the conceptual order — or a like necessity — also characterizes the relations between the concrete sense phenomena that actually exist in the ever changing conditions of space and time (cf. 219). Apparently, Mr. Joseph has failed to distinguish between the self-evidence of the abstract law of uniformity within the conceptual order, and the entirely different grounds on which the application of this law to the concrete, actual domain of sense experience must be maintained as valid. Jp. 382. a p. 390. 3 p. 382. The feeling that this method is not quite satisfactory seems to us to reveal that attitude of mind which would restrict the terms " knowledge " and "science" to self-evident truths, and conclusions derived from these by cogent demonstrative reasoning. 4 We interpret Mr. Joseph's account of the principle, as given in his Logic, pp. 380, 391, to propound the view that this principle is " unconditional " ; that we know it to be " unconditional," because, although it is not self-evident, the facts force us to admit it, because the denial of it would " resolve the universe into items that have no intelligible connexion ". But this implies that the law is based on experience, and reached a posteriori. Yet, elsewhere he seems to hold that the principle is self-evident : cf. p. 390, n. (n. n, p. 107) ; also p. 401, where he writes: " The law of the uniformity of nature itself, as we have seen, is not arrived at in that way [i.e. a posteriori], since if we once doubt it, it is impossible to show that UNI FORM IT Y OF NA TURE 1 09 of course, not prior to, but in and with, all our experience ; l but when we seek rational grounds for our assumption of it, where can these be found but in the facts, in our experience ? When a law is established by this pro cedure, we must, of course, recognize that "had the facts been otherwise, we need not have admitted the law ; and [that] we do not see, except on the hypothesis that the law is true, why the facts might not have been other wise ".2 This is the reason why Mr. Joseph regards such procedure as unsatisfactory ; but if we believe in the law of uniform causation because it is the only principle that will "account for the facts of our experience," surely we must be prepared to admit that "had the facts been otherwise we need not have admitted the law " ; 3 and in this there can be nothing unsatis factory. But if this is the way we justify our belief in the law, then, obviously, that belief is not a prerequisite condition for experience, entirely prior to, and independent of, experience, but is rather psychologically simultaneous with, and philosophically grounded on, experience. Thirdly, it must be carefully noted that the abstract, hypothetical law — which alone is self-evident, being, in fact, reducible to the principle of identity, as Mr. Joseph shows, and as we have already pointed out — does not and cannot, of itself , "account for the facts of our experience". It belongs to the conceptual or ideal order, the order of abstract objects of intellectual thought ; whereas " the facts of our experience " belong to the phenomenal order, i.e. is to the order of realities actually existing in space and time, and subject to all the changeful conditions of such existence. But no purely abstract, conceptual principle can, of itself, account for the actual existence or permanence, in space and time, of the present " choir of heaven and furniture of earth".4 It is the categorical principle alone — " Nature has been, is, and will be, and must be, uniform "—that can give us any intelligible account of the actual world of our experience, as distinct from a merely hypothetical world constructed by our own thought from intellectual concepts. And hence the supreme importance of determining in what sense nature must be uniform, of "discussing what we mean by"5 this "must," and of assigning a rational ground for our belief in this necessity, in the sense in which we interpret it. Fourthly, as already explained, we believe this "necessity," this "must," to be conditional, contingent, dependent on the Fiat of a Divine and All-wise the facts are any more consistent with its falsity than with its truth ". The abstract principle is, of course, self-evident, but the validity of its application to the actual world of sense experience is not. 1 It is quite true that " if we once doubt" the truth of the principle as applied to the actual universe, " it is impossible to show that the facts are any more con sistent with its falsity than with its truth " (op. cit., p. 401), or, in fact, to reason at all about events in space and time beyond actual experience ; but from this it does not follow that assent to the principle must be antecedent to, and independent of, all experience. The principle, even in its applied sense, is not reached by any process of logical inference. None the less, it is based on experience. From experience we abstract the concepts embodied in the principle. Experience suggests the abstract principle as validly applicable to the real world ; we assume that it is so applicable ; and further experience justifies the assumption. 2 JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 382. 3ibid. 4 C/. MELLONE, op. cit., p. 282. 5 JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 390. no THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC Greater and Ruler, whose existence and providence can be proved from " the facts of our experience " : to us the principle means that " The course of physical nature must be uniform if, and provided that, and in so far as, the will of God makes it so ". If, then, we wish to formulate an ultimate, uncon ditional, or absolutely necessary, law, for physical nature, or indeed for all contingent reality, we shall find it in the simple statement that "The whole course of contingent or created reality must be as God, the Necessary Being, wills it to be ". If we accept J. S. Mill's definition of laws of nature in the strict sense, as " the fewest and simplest assumptions, which being granted, the whole existing order of nature would result " ; * the law we have just enun ciated would be the really ultimate "law of nature," though this was very far indeed from Mill's own thought. We have already referred to Mill's in ability to transcend the " conditional," or to give any account of the nature of that ultimate, outstanding condition on which "the present constitution of things " 3 is dependent. Let us see whether Mr. Joseph is any more expli cit in regard to the nature of this final and most important condition. Understanding a law to be unconditional when its truth is not dependent on any outstanding condition other than those explicitly stated in the formula tion of the law,3 he goes on to inquire : " are there any unconditional laws known to us?"4. He first refers to the mechanical view of the physical universe, which purports to interpret and explain " all physical changes " as "determined altogether according to physical laws," and to be all "purely mechanical":5 according to which view these mechanical laws, while con ditioning the existence and course of all physical nature, would be themselves unconditional. He very rightly declines to accept this view on the ground that it is " impossible to account on physical principles for the facts, of conscious ness " 8 . . . " Thus to a physical theory of the world consciousness remains unaccountable ; such a theory therefore cannot be complete or final ".7 He then suggests in a mild way that " we are perhaps sometimes too hasty in supposing that we see the necessary truth of physical principles ".8 Such a supposition is, of course, not only too hasty, but also erroneous, seeing that such principles, referring as they do to the order of concrete physical facts, cannot have the purely abstract necessity of mathematical truths : " it might be said that in the first law of motion it is self-evident indeed that a body will persist in its state of rest or uniform rectilinear motion until something interferes with it, but not that interference can come only from another body ; that the mathe matical reasoning in physical science is necessary, but not the physical prin ciples which supply the data to which mathematical reasoning is applied ; and that the doctrine that a body can only be interfered with by another body is one of these ".9 All this points to the conclusion that " the fundamental physical laws are only conditionally true," 10 that is, dependent on conditions 1 Logic, III., iv., § i. * Logic, III., v., § 6: cf. supra, 219. 3 JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 381. 4p. 382. *ibid. 9ibid. 7p. 384. 8ibid. 9 p. 385 (italics are ours, except the last). The assertion that " a body can only be interfered with by another body " is not really a physical "principle," nor can physics even prove it to be true : what it is meant to convey is simply this, that "physical science prescinds from all but material agencies " (Cf. MAKER, Psychology, p. 518, n. 30), "ibid. UNIFORMITY OF NA TURE 1 1 1 which are not themselves physical, and whose nature, therefore, it is beyond the scope of physical science as such to explain : " supposing that there are, if we may so put it, spiritual conditions upon which the movements of bodies in the last resort depend . . . then physical science at any rate cannot deal with those conditions "-1 Of course it cannot, since it does not purport to deal with all reality : but we expect from the physical scientist that he should not go on to deny the existence of such conditions merely because they fall beyond his scope and methods as a scientist : 2 he is doing a real service to his science by recognizing its limitations. But physical science and philosophy are both brought into disrepute by those who gratuitously deny the existence of ultra- physical conditions and causes, who contend that mechanical laws are uncon ditional, and that all existing reality can be explained by these laws, when, as a matter of fact, such laws offer no ultimate explanation even of the material universe. Mr. Joseph fails to note, however, that there is this still more funda mental reason for rejecting the mechanical view : that it purports to explain the actual, concrete existence and uniform course of nature, by the mere formu lation of some one or some few mechanical laws. How could any abstract, intellectual formula about atoms, mass, motion, energy, etc. — even were such a formula self-evident — account for the actual existence and course of nature ? An abstract law cannot account for existing facts, or for the uniformity or necessity 3 of actual processes. Actual facts demand an actual cause, and so does the mode— whether uniform, or necessary, or otherwise — in which they happen. If, then, all physical nature is dependent on, and refers us to, an ultra-physical or spiritual domain of reality, and if even the highest and widest physical laws are not absolutely ultimate, but conditioned by the reality or realities of this other domain, it is obviously the highest duty of the philo sopher to determine the nature and influence of these conditions. But is it not also the duty of the logician to take note of, and call attention to, all the leading alternative ways in which these conditions have been, or may be, con ceived by philosophers ? or at least not to convey the impression that these alternatives are fewer than they really are ? Now, according to Mr. Joseph, if we are dissatisfied with the " mechanical " alternative, " philosophy suggests 1 JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 385. zcf. MAHER, Psychology, p. 420: "The student should always remember that physical science simply assumes the law of uniform causation ; that its universality is merely a postulate to be justified only in metaphysics ; and that the metaphysician, who recognizes moral convictions to be not less real nor less weighty facts than those of physical science, is bound to qualify, limit, or interpret the law when applied to moral actions in accordance with his wider and more comprehensive view of ex perience". C/. also pp. 517-24, especially p. 519, n. 32. 3 It is no ultimate explanation of this necessity to say that it is " mechanical ". If all nature is merely one vast machine or mechanism, who made it ? The neces sity we ascribe to the course of actual nature in time and space is not the necessity we ascribe to abstract judgments about possible essences : it is not purely intellectual : it is a manifestation of intelligence and will and power. The only immediate source it can have is our experience of the order, regularity, uniformity of all nature, compel ling us to interpret the latter as a cosmos, as the work of an Omnipotent Will directed by Supreme Wisdom. The only necessity for which we can rationally account in actual nature is that by which it pursues the course marked out for it by the Divine Fiat. To say as a last word about the course of nature that it is "mechanical," is no better than to ascribe it to mere chance, or to pronounce it an insoluble enigma. 1 1 2 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC that in the last resort, instead of explaining consciousness in terms of physical law, we shall have to see in physical law a manifestation of intelligence. The whole material order is an object of apprehension ; therein, however it stands related to minds that apprehend it, it and they together form the complete reality, or res completa ; and they cannot be understood except together ". ' As a final word on the problem, this is hardly satisfactory. At least, the statement might be a little more explicit. In justification, presumably, of his brevity, the author adds : " It is not our business to discuss here this central metaphysical problem ". That is so ; but from what he does say, and leave unsaid, about it, we are left in doubt whether or not he is really committing himself to the philosophy of idealistic or spiritualistic monism. " The whole material order," and " minds," " together form the complete reality, or res com pleta" That sounds like monism. A few pages further on he writes : " If the whole series of events in time can be regarded as an expression of the activity of that which is in some way exempt from subjection to succession, then what appears in time as future may have to be taken into account in giving a reason for the present and the past, though of course the future cannot determine the present in the same way as what precedes it does ".2 But this statement — which apparently refers to the influence of final cause, or purpose, in the course of events — is equally compatible with theism or with spiritualistic monism. And we get no clue as to which alternative the author himself adopts ; he merely adds : " The present chapter is perhaps already more than sufficiently metaphysical ". But there is a graver inconvenience in his treatment of the question : what he has managed to say, and to leave unsaid, may seriously mislead the student. When he chose to set over against the mechanical, materialist view of nature, the Ideological, spiritualist view, he made mention of only one form of spiritualism, the pantheistic or monistic form. Why has he passed over in silence the other well-known alternative, the philosophy of theism ? Theism is at least a pos sible alternative to monism. Therefore it claims a mention from the logician. But, according to Mr. Joseph, if we reject mechanical materialism, " philosophy suggests that in the last resort, instead of explaining consciousness in terms of physical law, we shall have to see in a physical law a manifestation of in telligence ".3 Philosophy does not suggest this as a " last resort ". And, even if it did, the suggestion would be ambiguous : Of what intelligence are we to re gard physical law as a manifestation ? our own individual intelligences ? or an immanent cosmic intelligence — an anima mundi f an intelligence "with will, or one without will ? an unconscious, or a self-conscious, intelligence ? And what sort of manifestation ? — a manifestation of one reality, itself to itself, by an inner process of self-evolution, so that the one reality is substance and pro cess and law and cause and effect all at once ? These are all various forms or phases of monism, which " philosophy," i.e. mature reflection on the facts of experience, may suggest. But, besides all of them, philosophy has at all times persistently suggested an alternative omitted by Mr. Joseph, the alter native which we believe to be the true one, viz., that physical law is a manifestation, to men's minds, of the intelligence and will of a Necessaiy, Self-existent, Divine, All-perfect Being, really distinct from the finite, con tingent, dependent, and conditioned universe of sense experience, the " world '' 1 JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 384. 2 p. 390, n. D p. 384 (italics ours). UNIFORMITY OF NA TURE 1 1 3 which He has freely created, conserves, and rules, according to the eternal dic tate of that wisdom whose work must needs be a cosmos. The explicit men tion of theism, as at least a possible alternative to mechanical materialism and monistic spiritualism, would have considerably enhanced the value of Mr. Joseph's able treatment of the uniformity of causation. We pointed out already, in connexion with the principle of sufficient reason (215), as well as in the preceding paragraphs, that it is a mistake in method to suppose that we must justify the particular view of nature as a whole, or the particular interpretation of its uniformity, on which we base our inductions and inferences, before we proceed to make any of those inductions or inferences. It is one thing to set out in the investigation or discovery of truth by making certain assumptions, and to justify these assumptions in due course : it is another thing altogether to demand an ultimate justification of them before we set out at all, and as a con dition for setting out. The former procedure is rational, the latter de mand is irrational. While, for instance, it is undoubtedly true that unless reality were intelligible, knowledge would be impossible ; it does not fol low that this truth must be explicitly assumed and placed as the necessary foundation and starting-point of all search for truth ; just as we saw that it is not necessary to assume a knowledge of the existence of an All-wise Ruler of nature before believing anything else about nature. We must start by assuming these principles of sufficient reason, causality, and unifor mity : they are presuppositions of induction : it is by experience — in the broadest sense — that we afterwards justify them. There is an analogous assumption discussed in epistemology regarding the capacity of the mind to discover truth : an intelligible reality and facul ties capable of understanding it are necessary for an actual knowledge of reality, but to prove beforehand that our faculties are capable does not seem to be a necessary condition for arriving at such actual knowledge of reality. A good stomach and wholesome food are necessary for a good digestion ; but a knowledge that we have either the one or the other is by no means necessary for the desired result. The sceptic has no right to prejudge the question of the possibility of knowledge, or to decide it in the negative sense ; but neither does it seem justifiable to prejudge it and decide it a priori in the positive sense. It may not be decided a priori, but only by experience, by testing our faculties, by letting them work and observing their mode of operation. No doubt, it is the self-same faculty, which, by reflection, observes and estimates the value of its own operations. But this involves us in no circulus vitiosus ; for the philosopher's critical reflection on the spontaneous workings of his own cognitive faculties does not purport to be a logical proof of their soundness, but a psychological process by which he proceeds to guarantee their soundness to himself, and to satisfy himself that they have not been deluding him. And if the reflecting mind sees no reason to doubt the validity of its own spontaneous assents, after a careful examination of these, it is justified in rejecting scepticism as unreasonable. This larger question, however, is not for logic, but for epistemology. 225. RELATION OF THE PRINCIPLE TO INDUCTION AND TO DEDUCTION. — Passing now to the second question raised above VOL. II. 8 114 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC (223, p. 99), we may inquire what is the precise role played by the principle of uniformity in every process by which we establish inductively a general physical law : what exactly is its relation to induction? The principle is a standard according to which we generalize, both formally and materially, every abstract rela tion of cause and effect which we discover in the physical uni verse ; it is a rule of the widest generality, the indefinite scope of which we gradually realize by the application of it to wider and wider generalizations in various departments of nature. If we have determined, by the methods of inductive analysis, that a certain kind or species of physical agency, A, is the physical cause of a, we can forthwith generalize our discovery that " A as such is the physical cause of a" by stating that " Whenever and wherever A is operative, there will a be found " ; and in doing this we are only making a special application of the wider prin ciple of uniformity which tells us that "Whatever can be predi cated of a physical cause or nature in the abstract (as causally connected therewith) can be predicated of all instances of that cause or nature ". It is not that the general law of uniformity is reached first, and the narrower law (that "A will produce a") deduced logically from it. In neither case — and indeed in no case — is the discovery of a general law a ratiodnative process, a logical inference (197, 212). Inference may have been involved in the subsidiary processes by which we verify the abstract judgment "A as such is the physical cause of a"; but the immediate mental process by which the law is reached is a process of judg ment (following on abstract conception), not a logical inference in the strict sense of a conscious derivation of one judgment from another, or others, which imply the former logically.1 But if in duction is riot an inference, there can be no meaning in the statement we meet so commonly in logical treatises, that the principle of uniformity is the major premiss — whether immediate or remote — of every induction? The principle does not help us to reach the abstract -truth connecting cause and effect (" A as such is the physical cause of a "). It is in generalizing the latter (to " All 1 Cf. JOYCE, op. cit., pp. 217, 227 ; though elsewhere he defines induction as the " legitimate inference of universal laws from individual cases " (p. 215) : he uses the word here, presumably in the wide sense of derivation, not in the sense of a logically "inferential process" in which the principle of uniformity would be a major premiss (p. 218). Cf. supra, 212. SC/. Palaestra Logica, p. 130; MELLONE, op. cit., p. 384; MILL, Logic, III., in., § i. UN I FOR MIT Y OF NA TURE 1 1 5 A's will produce a") that the principle finds a partial applica tion ; just as in applying this generalized truth to particular cases by the syllogism, the Aristotelean Dictum de omni is partially applied. There is, therefore, a sense in which the law of unifor mity bears a relation to the mental ascent from particular to universal, analogous to that which the axiom of the Aristotelean syllogism, the Dictum de omni, bears to the descent from universal to particular (170, 191). Every deductive syllogism in the first figure is a special or narrower application of the Dictum. For instance, the syllogism "Man is mortal, Socrates is a man, therefore Socrates is mortal " may be thus expressed : " Mortality, which is predicated of the class man, can be similarly predicated of Socrates, who belongs to that class " ; from which it appears, too, that the Dictum cannot be regarded as an ultimate major premiss of all syllogisms in the first figure, but rather as a fundamental, standard syllogism (?All M is P; S is M ; therefore S is P"} symbolizing that type of mental process, and by its self-evidence justifying the latter (I92).1 So, too, induction is a distinct mental process of ascent from particular to universal ; and every such ascent is a narrower and more special exercise of the fundamental, standard, typical in duction, by which we reach the widest law of physical nature, viz. that natural causes act uniformly — that whatever (a) has been dis covered to be really due to a physical cause (A] in any observed instance or instances, will be always and everywhere produced by that cause. And, just as the Dictum de omni is not a principle whose truth must be consciously grasped by the mind beforehand, as a condition for reasoning validly by the syllogism, but is rather a generalization of the syllogistic process, implicitly involved in every syllogism and explicitly grasped only by a deliberate, reflex analysis of this process itself, so the principle of the uni formity of nature is not a truth which must be grasped as a logical antecedent to justify the generalization made in each separate induction, but is rather itself a wider induction partially involved in every special induction, and explicitly grasped and formulated in its fulness only when the mind comes to analyse those special inductions afterwards.2 1 C/. VENN, op. cit., p. 126 : " When the Dictum was assigned as the ground of the individual inference, all that we were doing was to generalize this latter ". a Mr. JOSEPH (op. cit., pp. 407, 408) rightly rejects the view that uniformity of 8* n6 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC It was not by supposing " belief in uniformity " to be " by no means the earliest of our beliefs," but in supposing it to be reached by a certain kind of " inference," while at the same time supposing this kind of "inference" to depend for its validity on an antecedent profession of this belief, that Mill fell into the fallacy of petitio principii : just as we should fall into the fallacy were we to suppose that our knowledge of the Dictum de omni is an antecedent condition for the validity of the syllogism, and is itself reached by a syllogism. Belief in the uniformity of nature (in the categorical sense) is not a mental assent which must pre cede every induction we make : it is partially embodied in each, and is gradually extended by us to all nature. In every scientific induction of a physical law, belief in the uniformity of nature is, therefore, operative. For we embrace the belief that the causes we are dealing with are necessitating causes (i.e. causes invariably followed by the same effects), when, in the first or abstractive stage of the process, we convince our selves, from an observed case or cases, that "the nature A is necessarily connected with the effect a ".l And in the second or generalizing stage, in which we pass from this abstract judgment to the universal judgment, " All A's will always and everywhere produce a" we still more explicitly assent to what is a partial application of the general principle that "in the real order the same cause does always actually produce the same effect".2 But, if the principle of the uniformity of nature is thus shown to be a general expression or summing up of the mental process by which we pass from observed cases, through \\ieabstract, to the universal judgment — front "Some (observed) J/'s are P," through " M as such is P" to "All ATs are P" : is not the self-same principle equally involved in the downward process by which we pass deductively or syllogistically from the universal "All M's are P " to its special applications in the conclusions " These or those S's, which are (other, new, hitherto unobserved) M's, are nature " is the ultimate major premiss of all inductions". He further admits that " it is not, indeed, necessary, in a particular investigation, to assume this uniformity to extend beyond the department of facts with which we are dealing"; but con tends that it is, though only partially applied, nevertheless universally assumed, in every particular induction (p. 407). It is not so assumed explicitly ; but when we come to reflect on the grounds of our inductions we see that the universal principle was implicit or latent in them : that otherwise we could not make our experience intelligible : that our success in making experience intelligible through it justifies our belief in it. 1 JOYCE, op. cit., p. 219. *ibid. UNIFORMITY OF NA TURE 1 1 7 also P " ? Undoubtedly, the principle of uniformity is involved in the application of the syllogism to any actual sphere of reality. The Dictum de omni informs us that "Whatever can be predi cated of a class can be predicated about any member of the class ". But in order to make the predication about any new instance of a class in any actual sphere, we must (a) identify the instance as a member of that class, and (£) assume that all the members have a stable, uniform nature, which constantly demands the same predicates.^ When dealing with the merely formal aspect of the syllogism, we regarded the terms of the latter as expressing abstract con cepts of possible class-essences, apart from the question of their verification or realization in any actual sphere of reality. We supposed each abstract thought-object to be fixed, stable, un changing. We had not, therefore, to raise the question whether there is really a corresponding uniformity, regularity, stability, in the actual spheres within which we suppose these concepts to apply. It is when we pass from the purely formal and hypothetical processes of arranging and dividing abstract concepts logically according to intension and extension, and then reasoning " con sistently " from them, — to the material and. categorical processes of classifying things, of verifying our definitions of the latter, and reasoning " truly" or "demonstratively " about them, — that we feel called upon to justify our belief in that real uniformity in things, which is the objective ground and condition of our thinking, judging, and reasoning rightly about them.2 Dr. Venn, in his Empirical Logic? asks the interesting ques tion : How is it that an analysis of induction raises the question as to the origin of our belief in the uniformity of nature, while no corresponding difficulty is supposed to be felt in respect of deduction ? He takes the example of a man bitten by a cobra. 1C/. JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 378 ; MELLONE, op. cit., p. 252 (referring to Ueberweg, Logic, § 101) : " the worth of the syllogism as a form of knowledge depends on the assumption that general laws of causation hold in nature, and may be known ". 2 " Geometrical proofs rest on the intuition of spatial relations, and algebraic on the intuition of quantitative relations. . . . In fact, our belief in the uniformity of space, and in the uniform formation of the numerical series, stands to mathematical reasoning as our belief in the uniformity of nature stands to inductive. Deny them, and in either case no general proposition remains possible any longer. Nay more, no demonstration remains possible even about a particular case." — JOSEPH, Logic, pp. 506, 507. 3 p. 124. n8 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC We believe the man will die. We may assign our reason in either of two ways : — "Deductive: All men who are bitten die. The man XY is bitten. Therefore XY will die. " Inductive : The men A, B, C . . . were bitten and died. The man XY has also been bitten. Therefore XY will die." Ask him who gives the deductive answer why he considers that the reason he assigns is a sufficient one : he will tell you that it is so because " what holds good of a class holds good of every member of that class ". Now ask a similar question of him who gave the inductive answer : ask him why does he consider the fact that " A, B, C . . . and all men who have been bitten died " to be a sufficient reason for believing that XY will die : he will tell you finally that he considers it to be a sufficient reason " be cause nature is uniform ". Now, why is the man who gives the deductive answer let alone at this point and not called on to explain why he believes that " what holds good of a class holds good of every member of that class," while the man who gives the inductive answer is not let alone, but has to justify his belief that " nature is uniform " ? The only reason for difference of treatment would be because the deductive reasoner is not supposed to be concerned with the application of his class-concepts to the real world, but only with their consistency within the sphere of abstract thought, in which they have been conceived as fixed, static, unchanging : while the inductive reasoner is supposed to be concerned with the real validity of those concepts, with their application to the real world, and, therefore, with the existence of uni formity in the real world itself. But the moment a person attempts to apply a syllogism within any domain of actual reality — in other words, to demonstrate or prove anything as true — he is committing himself to a belief in the " uniformity of nature " regarding certain classes of things within that domain. Hence, those logicians who are inclined to view their science as concerned exclusively with the consistency of thought refuse to go behind such ultimate logical generalizations as the Dictum de omni and the Uniformity of nature for the pur pose of justifying these. Understanding by a logical ground or reason for assent to a judgment, always some wider generalization which includes the latter (198), they observe that there is no pos sible wider generalization than either of the two in question ; and UNIFORMITY OF NA TURE 1 1 9 they conclude that the justification of our assent to such principles falls within the province of psychology or metaphysics, rather than of logic.1 JOSEPH, Logic, chap, xix., pp. 407 sqq. VENN, Empirical Logic, chaps, iv., v., and xv. JOYCE, Logic, chap. xv. MILL, Logic, III., iii., iv., v., and xxi. MERCIER, Logique, pp. 326 sqq. MELLONE, Introd. Text-book of Logic, pp. 1.^0 sqq. MAKER, Psychology, pp. 420, 517-24. WELTON, op. cit., ii., pp. 1-30. 1 C/. VENN, op. cit., p. 128. CHAPTER V. HYPOTHESIS : ITS NATURE, FUNCTIONS, AND SOURCES. 226. FUNCTIONS OF SCIENTIFIC HYPOTHESIS.— We have seen that the aim of science is to discover the causes and laws by which we may explain the facts of our experience. Our know ledge of these causes and laws is embodied in universal judgments, and these universal judgments it is the function of induction to establish. But we can neither discover nor verify a universal judgment unless we are first led somehow or other to suspect or suppose it to be true. Such suspicion or supposition we call an hypothesis. Not every supposition, however, is an hypothesis in the strict or scientific sense of this term. For example, in order to help our imagination in the study of phenomena due to gravity, we suppose that if the total mass of a body were concentrated in a mathematical point, called the centre of gravity of the body, that point would manifest the same force and have the same weight as the whole body. We imagine the earth as a mathematical point. We conceive its total gravitation-force to be concentrated in that point — its " centre of gravity ". We find it easier in this way to measure that force, to bring home to ourselves the law by which it acts on bodies on or near the earth's surface, than if we tried to conceive the several particles of the earth's mass acting each in its own place and independently of the others, on those bodies. But we know, all the time, that the latter is really the case, that our conception of " centre of gravity " has no fact for its object, that the conception is from beginning to end a mere fancy, a purely subjective conception having no other object than an imagined possibility.1 Again, in order to help ourselves to conceive great distances or magnitudes we often have recourse to mental images which we call suppositions. To realize the distance of the moon from 1 C/. MERCIER, Logique, p. 339. 120 HYPOTHESIS 121 the earth we may suppose or imagine a cannon-ball travelling at a velocity of five hundred yards per second and reaching the moon after eight days : that image helps us to bring home to our selves a distance so great that a mere statement of the number of miles in it can hardly be pictured by us. But such a supposi tion is not what we understand by a scientific hypothesis: it belongs to the sphere of imagination exclusively, while a scientific hypothesis is ^judgment bearing on our knowledge of reality. The image of the cannon-ball gives us a clearer apprehension of some thing we already knew ; an hypothesis aims at teaching us some thing we did not know before.1 Here is a simple example of a scientific hypothesis : The juice of the grape ferments : the origin and nature of fermentation were at one time unknown : Pasteur conjectured that it was due to germs that swarm on the grapes, leaves, and stems, of the vine-tree. That was a scientific hy pothesis. An hypothesis , therefore, is an attempt at explanation : a pro visional supposition made in order to explain scientifically some fact or phenomenon. The construction of hypotheses is not confined to the induc tive sciences. The process described in connexion with deductive reasoning, by Aristotle and his mediaeval commentators, as "tn- ventio medii" " discovery of a middle term," i.e. of true and proper premisses to prove a conclusion, is really identical with what we nowadays call the conception or construction of an hypothesis. But it is in the positive or inductive sciences that hypothesis plays an all-important role. And in these sciences we understand by it the conception or supposition of some cause or law capable of explaining certain observed facts. Without hypothesis we can make no progress in scientific investigation. We cannot find the causes of phenomena without first suspecting their existence and whereabouts. Our experiments will lead nowhere unless made with the object of verifying some supposition. To direct our investigations along certain lines towards the dis covery of laws : such, in a word, is the function of hypothesis. All hypotheses should have their origin in the observed facts which we are attempting to explain (233, 234). But the actual conception of hypotheses is amenable to no logical rules. It is just here that the sagacity, genius, and originality, of the scientist and 1 Cf. MERCIER, Logique, p. 334. 122 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC inventor will have free scope (197). Wrong hypotheses will be usually conceived before right ones. Kepler is said to have conceived and disproved nineteen successively, before arriving at the laws of planetary motion.1 It must not, however, be imagined that hypotheses are useless unless they turn out to be true ; they often admirably fulfil their function of directing investigation, and do immense service to science, even though they be afterwards disproved. Thus, in astronomy we have the famous example ot the Ptolemaic or geocentric hypothesis, which gave place to the Copernican or heliocentric hypothesis in the sixteenth century. The conception of an hypothesis which is likely to prove useful, and helpful to the progress of science, is usually possible only to the well-trained mind that is stocked with information about the matter under investigation, and is accordingly quick to detect and utilize analogies. To such a mind, even the most commonplace facts may suggest invaluable lines of speculation and experiment — as the falling apple did for Newton, and the dancing lid of the steaming kettle did for Watt. Whewell was therefore right in emphasizing, as against Mill, the great import ance of hypothesis, or as he called it, "colligation of facts by means of an exact and appropriate conception," in the whole inductive process.2 But there are various kinds of hypotheses; and some are " more far-reaching in their effects than others ; for some are much more general, and apply to a much larger number and variety of facts. . . . Scientific hypotheses consist for the most part not in the mere coupling in the mind, as cause and effect, of two insulated phenomena (if the epithet may be allowed) : but in the weaving of a large number of phenomena into a coherent system by means of principles that fit the facts ".3 This brings us to the consideration of some of the principal types of scientific hypothesis. 227. SCIENTIFIC VALUE OF VARIOUS KINDS OF HYPOTHESIS. — We have described an hypothesis as a provisional explanation of certain observed facts. Now, we know a fact scientifically when we know all its causes, and the mode of its connexion with, or dependence on, these causes. If we take any phenomenon, or group of phenomena, involving within it a multiplicity of elements, changes, motions, activities — for example, the motions of the 1 C/. WELTON, op. cit., ii., pp. 66, 86. JOSEPH, op. cit., pp. 435-6. a Cf. WELTON, op. cit., pp. 48 sqq. JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 434. 3 JOSEPH, ibid., pp. 432, 433. HYPOTHESIS 123 planets, or the phenomena of the refraction and reflexion of light — we may conceive and verify hypotheses as to the exact quantitative relations between those various elements and motions, without for the time inquiring either into their origin or their raison ctetre, their efficient or their final causes. We may, by accurate observation and experiment, seek to arrive at an exact quantitative expression of the various events and agencies which make up the whole phenomenon. We may aim, in other words, at weighing and measuring the facts, at describing them with mathematical precision, at establishing formulae which will be " descriptive statements of the exact character of the phenomena to be explained, when their relations to other phenomena are not in question " ; * at reaching expressions which will describe concisely and accurately the quantitative side of those phenomena. Now, the scientist's supposition or conjecture as to the exact quantitative relation or ratio between some or all of the various elements or motions in a given series of phenomena, has been commonly called an Hypothesis of Law. And when such sup position is verified, and formulated in clear and concise language, it is what is commonly recognized in the physical sciences as a Physical Law. A " law " of nature, in this sense of the term,2 tells us "how" a phenomenon takes place, i.e. in what exact measure and proportion the various constituent agencies and energies must be present and operative ; it is simply an exact mathematical description of the measure in which a certain phenomenon regularly occurs. Such, for example, are the " laws " of refraction and reflexion of light ; or the " law " which states that the strength of an electric current varies directly as the electromotive force and inversely as the resistance of the circuit ; or the "law" of gravitation, that any two bodies in the universe tend to move towards each other with an acceleration that varies directly as the product of their masses and inversely as the square of their distance apart : " The business of physical science," writes Mach, " is . . . the abstract quantitative expres sion of facts. The rules which we form . . . [for this purpose] ... are the laws of nature." 3 But though this mathematical measurement of phenomena gives us a clearer description of them, still it does not give us a 1 WELTON, Logic, vol. ii., p. 91. "For another and deeper sense of this expression, see above, 217. *apud WELTON, loc. cit. i24 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC full insight into them, it does not explain them ; for explanation reveals not merely how, or in what manner, an event happens, when it does happen ; but also why it happens (its final cause), and what makes it happen (its origin or efficient cause). And while, as physical scientists, we may seek to establish " physical laws," in the sense of quantitative descriptions of the relations between the various elements of a given regularly recurring phenomenon, we cannot, as rational beings, rest content with such partial explana tion, but are impelled by our nature to ask ourselves further about the " whence " and the " wherefore " of the whole pheno menon, and so to connect it with all its causes. We cannot help asking those further questions, because the " sufficient reason " of any phenomenon is not to be found in the isolated phenomenon itself, but in the sum-total of all its causes. The Positivist school of philosophers would, indeed, have science study " only the laws of phenomena, and never the mode of production " * of these phenomena by their causes. But science — or philosophy — will insist on studying the latter. Man z£/z//and must seek the causes, both efficient and final, as well as the mere description and measure, of the phenomena surrounding him. And the hypotheses he makes about the causes of any given phenomenon — as distinct from those he makes with a view to arriving at a more exact quantitative presentation and description of the constituent parts of the phenomenon — have been called, in contradistinction to the latter, Hypotheses of Cause. For example, Newton's gravitation hypothesis was an Hypothesis of Law in so far as it simply aimed at giving an exact quantitative expression or description of the various relations of mass, distance, and rate of motion, that make up the whole complex group of phenomena presented to us in our experience of falling bodies and of the motions of the moon and the planets : and in so far as the conception of " gravitation " includes all these phenomena in one common quantitative description, it has been verified, and is now an established "theory "or "law". That is to say, we now recognize as a verified and accurate de scription of the manner and measure in which these motions of matter occur throughout the universe, the statement that " the acceleration with which any two distant bodies in the universe, Mj and M2, tend to move towards each other through space, 1 WELTON, Logic, vol. ii., p. 91. HYPOTHESIS 125 varies directly as the product of M; and M2, their masses, and inversely as the square of their distance (D2) asunder — But, beyond all this lies the question as to what is the de termining cause of those motions. And as to this, we are indeed free to assume that it is a certain natural property, an active power or force (228), in the bodies themselves, in virtue of which they determine or bring about these motions in this precise manner and measure. But beyond the mere fact, which the principle of causality forces us to admit, that there is in the bodies which constitute the visible universe some adequate cause of those motions, some force that produces them, we know as yet practically nothing. What is the nature of that force? How does it determine and bring about those motions whose magni tude we can accurately estimate by an already verified law? What sort is that influence? How is it exerted through space, independently, as it would appear, of intervening bodies? We describe it as " attraction," but what idea does this term convey to our minds ? Thus, as to the nature of the cause in question, as to what kind the force of gravity is, and how it acts, we are still largely in the dark. Here, then, is a field for further hypotheses, hypotheses of cause, whose purport will be to explain the known fact of gravitation. Various hypotheses have been framed at different times to connect this fact with the hypotheti cal all-pervading ether, and with the fundamental constitution of matter.1 So far, however, these are conjectures hazarded to help our imagination in picturing the phenomenon to ourselves, rather than possible explanations of it. Hypothesis, as we have de fined it (226), is essentially explanatory : a supposition that does not offer an explanation of phenomena, but merely aids us in conceiving and describing them, would appear to fall outside our definition. Every hypothesis of cause, i.e. every supposition of some definite antecedent (or group of antecedents) as being the real, actual cause of the phenomenon in question, is necessarily explanatory : it offers — provisionally — an explanation of the phenomenon. Hypotheses of law, on the other hand, in so far as they merely describe with mathematical exactness the manner in which phenomena occur, are rather descriptive than explanatory ; but nevertheless, inasmuch as a correct quantitative estimate of 1 Cf. NYS, Cosmologie, p. 125. LESAGE, The Unseen Universe, § 140. PICTET, &tudc critique du materialisme et du spiritualisme, p. 239. 126 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC those changes or activities suggests or reveals to us, at least partially, the nature of their causes and of the laws according to which these causes interact — for " operari sequitur esse" — and inasmuch as hypotheses of law thus inevitably suggest hypotheses of cause, the former as well as the latter have some claim to be called hypotheses in the stricter sense, i.e. explanatory hypotheses. Some hypotheses, whether they appear descriptive or ex planatory, may be recognized from the beginning as having little or no probability. We may know so little about some unfamiliar, unexplored, complex, many-sided phenomena — such as those of electricity, for example — as to be scarcely able to make any sup position at all as to their real nature, laws, and causes. But some provisional supposition as to the nature of the agent we call electricity, is absolutely necessary if we want to collect, arrange, describe, and discuss, in intelligible language, its various manifesta tions, and their connexion with their supposed common cause. And this supposition, moreover, if it is to be of any use in help ing us towards an explanation of the phenomena, must be based on some analogy with some known agent. If we make any sup position at all, from which we can infer anything, about the un known thing we call "electricity," we must suppose the latter to be something resembling in some way or other some known natural agent. Accordingly, the supposition was made by Franklin, if only as a starting-point for investigation, and to see how it would work — in other words, as a working hypothesis, — that electricity was a fluid of some sort. This hypothesis, though scarcely probable, and merely " better than none," the best per haps in the circumstances, purported from the beginning to be mainly descriptive, but was none the less, of its nature, explanatory also, inasmuch as it supposed the real cause of the phenomena in question to be some sort of fluid. That hypothesis was never verified, and gradually lost ground, at least in its original form ; though the " electron " hypothesis, which is closely analogous to it, is now in turn taking the place of the two-fluid hypothesis. In other cases, however, such working hypotheses may for a long period grow steadily in probability according as they are found capable of explaining a larger area of phenomena, as did the Ptolemaic or geocentric hypotheses (in astronomy), with their cycloids and epicycloids to account for the apparent motions of the planets.1 So admirably did this group of hypotheses " ex- 1Cf. JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 435. HYPOTHESIS 137 plain" the known phenomena, that it was pretty generally (and erroneously) regarded, for centuries, as a fully verified or estab lished system. But, as St. Thomas pointed out with his character istically prudent reserve, some other hypothesis might perhaps account after all equally well — or even better — for the apparent motions of the heavenly bodies.1 And so after-events proved, culminating in the substitution of the Copernican for the Ptolemaic astronomy. Or again, two conflicting hypotheses may appear to account equally well for certain phenomena. These latter will be differ ently described on either hypothesis. And both descriptions will appear to be equally accurate. But evidently at least one of the descriptions must be de facto inaccurate : the assumptions involved in the very language used — based as this is on the supposition that the phenomena are of such and such a nature, due to such and such a cause, while they are quite otherwise in reality — such as sumptions necessarily falsify the whole description. We may conclude, then, that there is no fundamental differ ence between working, descriptive, and explanatory hypotheses, hypotheses of law, and hypotheses of cause, provided only and always that they are suppositions which have for their objects the REAL CAUSES of the observed phenomena, and the REAL LAWS accord ing to which the changes wrought by those causes in the observed phenomena actually take place. 228. NATURE AND VERIFICATION OF CAUSAL OR EXPLA NATORY HYPOTHESES.— The first essential, then, of a scientific hypothesis, is that it be a supposition of something real, equally real with the phenomenon it is to explain. This at once disposes of the class of suppositions referred to above (226), to which we have recourse merely in order the better to realize some pheno menon. But, furthermore, even when the object of our supposi tion is not a mere fancied possibility, when we mean the cause or law we are supposing, to be real, to be a fact, even then the ques tion arises : Have we always or necessarily a scientific hypothesis, as distinct from what some writers, for want of a better name, call systematic or synthetic conceptions ? 2 What sort, in other words, 1 " Licet enim talibus suppositionibus factis apparentia salvarentur, non tamen op- portet dicere has suppositiones esse veras, quia forte secundum aliquem alium modum, nondum ab hominibus comprehensum, apparentia circa Stellas salvantur." — In Lib. »i. De Ccelo et Mundo, 1. xvii. •MERCIER, op. cit., p. 338. 128 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC must we suppose our cause to be, in order that our supposition of its existence be a scientific hypothesis ? The controversy as to what kind or concept of cause it is legiti mate for us to employ in our hypotheses about the phenomena of nature, is one of very long standing. No supposition of ours, as to what is the cause of a phenomenon, will be of any use unless it be verifiable. But what kind of cause must we suppose to be operative, if our supposition is to be verifiable ? Newton insisted that the object of our hypothesis must be a vera causa, a real cause — meaning, thereby, to exclude arbitrary, fanciful, a priori suppositions and prejudices, not suggested by facts of experience. This, of course, is obviously right and proper. Must the cause, however, be supposed to be itself a phenomenon of some sort, i.e. something itself perceptible by the senses, so that the only valid verification of such hypothesis would be actual discovery, by sense perception, of the supposed cause, and actual observation of its visible causal connexion with the effect ? Such a requirement is rightly repudiated by scientists, though it is only such a sort of cause that answers to Mill's definition.1 Followers of Mill's phenomenist philosophy contend that it is a mere waste of time, and a hindrance to real scientific progress, to refer the various phenomena of mind, or of external nature, to corresponding " faculties " or " powers " or " forces " in either domain. And no doubt, such reference of individual effects, or classes of effects, to corresponding efficient principles, whether these be called " faculties " or " forces," would be calculated to retard further in vestigation, if such reference were taken as an ultimate rational explanation of those effects ; if, for instance, men were so foolish as to think they had said the last word as to why opium induces sleep by declaring opium to have a vis dormativa — to use the old familiar example. It is true that in the Renaissance period some of the decadent camp-followers of the great mediaeval Scholastics left themselves open to this reproach by taking refuge in such verbal explanations of natural phenomena.2 But up to quite 1 Logic, III., v., § 2. Cf. supra, p. 74, n. 3 ; infra, p. 131. 2C/. DE WULF, Scholasticism Old and New (2nd edition), pp. 147 sqq. ; His tory of Medieval Philosophy, p. 503. It was not, however, the fault of those mediaeval philosophers that the " forces " or " causes " in question were then, and are still for the most part, " occult," i.e. such that we have no positive imagination of the mode of their action. Modern scientists who are loudest in their ridicule of those " occult forces "are themselves obliged to have recourse to " motions " and " masses " and " ions" and " electrons " and " ids " and " biophors " and a whole host of such things, HYPOTHESIS 129 recent times it was the fashion with modern philosophers and scientists, in their boasted ignorance of mediaeval thought, to impute this and all manner of ab surdities to Scholasticism generally, and with the inevitable result that the ridicule they heaped upon their predecessors is now seen in the light of history to recoil upon their own heads. The thirteenth-century Scholastics, no less than their later critics, realized the importance of observation and experiment, the necessity of noting analogies between phenomena, of endeavouring by ana lysis of these analogies to reduce gradually, as far as possible, the number of distinct " forces," or " powers " postulated for the explanation of phenomena. They were never content to refer each separate phenomenon in nature to a distinct and corresponding cause supposed to be capable of producing that effect alone— to be sui generis, so to speak. They pushed investigation as far as the conditions of their time permitted. And those who, in modern times, have in herited the best traditions of Scholasticism, have always welcomed every careful attempt of the positive and experimental sciences to unify our experience of external nature by tracing large and varied and apparently unconnected fields of phenomena to the operation of some one or some few common " agencies ". They have nothing but approval for the methods whereby scientists have for mulated and tested hypotheses for the exploration of hitherto unsuspected natural " forces," or for the explanation of phenomena by referring these to already known " causes," with which such phenomena were previously thought to have no connexion. They themselves adopt these methods in physical science. They are not content to say that the varied phenomena of external nature must have causes, must be due to the operation — and co-operation — of nature's forces and agencies. They endeavour to discover in what groups of pheno menal antecedents the agencies productive of a given effect are operative. They try to bring to light " the sum-total of the [phenomenal, perceptible] con ditions, positive and negative taken together, the whole of the contingencies of every description, which being realized the consequent [effect or phenomenon] invariably follows " — which is Mill's own conception of the discovery of a "cause".1 And it is only when the inductive methods fail for want of ana logies on which to base hypotheses, i.e. in investigating the remoter causes of wider fields of phenomena, and the Ultimate Cause of the whole phenomenal universe, that they use the simple a posteriori argument to prove that such re moter causes— and such Ultimate Cause— must exist, and to discover about the nature of these just as much as the effects will warrant us in attributing to the latter. But Scholastics have held to the doctrine that while the senses stop at phenomena, intellect or reason can discover, in these phenomena, "substances," " causes," " faculties," " forces," which constitute and permeate the world of sense experience, and which reveal themselves to intellect by acting in and through the phenomena of sense. And they have held to this doctrine in obedience to such self-evident dictates of reason as that " every event must just quite as occult, in their own hypotheses. " How could masses and motions that must remain occult be anymore acceptable . . . than the occult powers of the ancient Scholasticism ? " — DUHEM, L' Evolution de lamecaniqtie, p. 190. Cf. Dublin Review , April, 1906, pp. 332, 337, where Professor Windle suggests a comparison of some of Weismann's hypotheses with the famous virtus dormativa. 1 Logic, iii., v., § 3. VOL. II. 9 1 30 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC have a cause," " every change must be a change of some state," and " every state must be a state of some subject or substance ". Of course, such principles will not of themselves unlock the secrets of science by telling us whether this and that event, or change, or state, have any underlying agencies, or causes, or substances in common, or how many of the latter there are in the world of sense experience altogether. Yet positivists and phenomenists appear to think that something like this should be expected from those principles. For, not rinding in the latter the key to any new positive information about nature, they proclaim that " substance," " power," " force," " efficiency," " purpose," etc. — in a word, all such objects of thought as lie beyond the ken of the senses — are " occult " and " unknowable," and should therefore be discarded.1 But as a matter of fact these objects are not " occult " to the intellect— of Positivists any more than of Scholastics. The former, despite their disclaimer of agnosticism, know just as much, or as little, about such objects of thought, as the latter : they discourse about " substances " and " causes " and " forces " and " faculties " no less than the latter : and we are all alike guided, in our ascent to such thought- objects from the data of sense, by the scholastic principle that from the operations of things we judge of their natures : operari sequitur esse ; qualis est operatio talis est natura. But positivists pretend to be able to " explain " the universe without calling in the aid of any " hyperphysical " entity 2 — we shall see presently with what effect, — and blame Scholastics for not discarding the " antiquated " metaphysics of " substance " and " accident," of " faculty," " power," and " force," in the philosophy of external nature. They have tried — unsuccessfully, of course — to deliver human reason from the supposed bondage of theology and meta physics, by eliminating from their system of thought all such " Scholastic " notions. We m£y be pardoned if we hesitate to exchange the " antiquated " system for the teaching of those later philosophers— who resolve all reality into " states " or " phases " or " processes," while denying that there is any sub stance or agent of which these are the states, phases, or processes ; or into a transient " flow " of sensations in the individual's consciousness, while denying that there is any permanent mind other than the said flow of sensations, or any abiding, substantial ego, or individual, to experience and interpret these sensations, and thus to remember past experience and to expect and anticipate future ex perience. The fact is that this phenomenist philosophy has made itself unin telligible by " divesting the human mind of its most fundamental conceptions " 3 — or, rather, by pretending to accomplish such a hopeless task : for it really smuggles into its explanations, at every turn, under the mask of a new termin ology of course, the very conceptions it pretends to dispense with. In opposition to the traditional philosophy of those so-called "occult" causes, Mill boldly proclaimed that he would deal only with causes which were themselves " phenomena," i.e. entities which would be in themselves perceptible by the senses : " I pre- 1 Cf. I. E. RECORD, April, 1910: " Some Current Phases of Physical Theories," p. 403 ; January, 19 10 : " The New Knowledge and its Limitations," p. 27. 3 Cf. I. E. RECORD, April, 1910, ibid. 3 WARD, Naturalism and Agnosticism, i., p. 65. Cf. I. E. RECORD, ibid., p. 400. HYPOTHESIS 131 mise," he wrote, " that when ... I speak of the cause of any phenomenon, I do not mean a cause which is not itself a pheno menon ; I make no research into the ultimate or ontological cause of anything".1 The trammels he thus sought to impose upon human thought were soon deemed too irksome, not only by philo sophers, but even by the scientists who professed a general sym pathy with the positivist philosophy. It is, indeed, conceivable that scientists might agree to confine their efforts exclusively to the discovery of coexistences and sequences between phenomena, and to eschew all thought and all mention of non-phenomenal or imperceptible entities, even as mere aids to investigation.2 But of course they have refused — and rightly — thus to debar themselves from using their imagination at all events, in addition to their senses. They have given a very wide interpretation indeed to the term "phenomenon," if the "causes" which they contemplate nowadays in their hypotheses are to be regarded as phenomena. Not only are some of the objects of current scientific hypotheses — i.e. some hypothetical causes of the phenomena of nature — not perceptible themselves by the senses, but they are not even in any true sense positively picturable by the imagination. We are very far removed indeed from the " phenomenal antecedents " of Mill when we are introduced into the domain of "ethers," "vortices," "corpuscles," "ions," and "electrons," by the physicist, or into the domain of " ids " and " biophors " and " biotic energies " by the physiologist. Indeed it is not so clear that scientists have not re turned to the " occult " entities of the " antiquated " metaphysics,3 and merely rebaptized, in a more mechanical terminology, the " materia prima " and "powers" and "efficiencies" and "vital forces " of Aristotle and the Scholastics ! As a matter of fact, it is now beginning to be recognized by scientists that all attempts to explain nature, whether organic or inorganic, by collocations and motions of material masses in space and time, i.e. by purely 1 Logic, 111., v., | 2. 3 C/. POINCARE, Science and Hypothesis, p. 223 : " The day will perhaps come when physicists will no longer concern themselves with questions which are inacces sible to positive methods, and will leave them to the metaphysicians. That day has not come yet ; man does not so easily .resign himself to remaining for ever ignorant of the causes of things." 3 See article, " Weismann and the Germ-Plasm Theory," in the Dublin Review, April, 1906, where Professor Windle suggests the comparison of Weismann's hy potheses with the "zns dormativa" and other such "virtutes occultae" of the older philosophy. C/. also, What is Life ? by the same author (Sands & Co., 1908) ; and I. E. RECORD, April, pp. 398 sqq. 9* 132 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC perceptible or picturable factors, and without the aid of purely con ceptual or intelligible factors, such as force, power, efficiency, pur pose and design, have proved futile; that concepts of hyperphysical entities and influences, however " occult " to sense or imagination, are indispensable for a rational explanation of nature's processes ; in a word, that the cause or principle of action which may be the object of a legitimate scientific hypothesis need not be itself a pheno menon, directly perceptible by the senses. It must, however, be such an agency, or group of agencies, that, though not directly perceptible itself, it is perceptible in its effects : it must be supposed to dwell in phenomena, to become operative in certain combinations of phenomena, and to produce therein directly perceptible effects. This indirect 'perceptibility of the supposed causes, in their effects, is necessary and sufficient for the object of a scientific hypothesis. In this way alone are "atoms," "elec trons," " ions," " sub-atomic motions," " biophors," and all the infinitesimally minute "causes " of modern scientific hypotheses, perceptible or " phenomenal " : in their effects, in the phenomena which they are supposed to actuate or constitute ; and in this they differ in no way from the " materia prima" "forma sub- stantialis" "qualities," "forces," "faculties," "natures," "pro perties," etc., of Scholasticism: for these too are perceptible indirectly, in their effects. Properly speaking, all such explanatory factors of our experience are " intelligible " or " noumenal," rather than " sensible " or " phenomenal ". The need that impels us to look for an explanation of sense experience obliges us to conjecture or suppose the real existence and operation of such — really supra-sensible— agencies. The whole process of conceiving the latter, and reasoning from such conceptions, is a process of the faculty which transcends the faculties of sense — the intellect. It makes comparatively little difference whether these conceptions, these hypothetical " causes," are more or less im mersed in, and supported by, concrete imagination-pictures.1 The visible, 1 It might, perhaps, be argued that hypotheses having for their objects abstract " powers," " forces," " natures," etc., in phenomena, cannot be so accurately verifi able, nor, therefore, so fruitful to science, as hypotheses which contemplate only such directly calculable factors as " atoms," " electrons," " undulations," etc. This is scarcely true, for mathematical values may be assigned to the former as easily as to the latter. It cannot be said that the British scientists have in any striking way excelled the French in their contributions to science ; yet the former have been always far more addicted than the latter to concrete, picturable, mechanical conceptions. C/. DUHEM, Evolution de la mecanique (Paris, 1903, ch. xv.) ; Professor Windle's article in the Dublin Review, already mentioned ; art. on " The Contrast of English and French Concepts of Physical Theories," by the Rev. P. DE VREGILLK in the Month, April, 1907, pp. 350 sqq. ; H. POINCARE'S Science and Hypothesis (Eng. HYPOTHESIS 133 measurable phenomena, in which they are supposed to be operative, are equally amenable to observation and experiment, whether the hypothetical " causes " be conceived as " properties," " forces," " affinities," " qualities ; " or as " atoms," " electrons " " vortices," " undulations," etc. Quantitative values may be assigned to such factors, by whatever names we call the latter. Since they are supposed to be factors operative in material phenomena, there must be a quantitative aspect in their modits operandi ; only we must not forget that this is not their sole aspect, and that we have not " explained " the facts fully by " calculating " the measiirable aspects of these factors. Yet this is likely to be forgotten by scientists who are influenced by the empirical philo sophy. Their tendency naturally is to assume that " all perceptible facts are measurable " 1 in terms of material masses and mechanical motions, and that science can attain to nothing that is not thus measurable. But, for instance, exhibitions of " talent, prudence or self-denial " 2 are perceptible facts. Yet, surely, their " magnitude " cannot be measured by any mechanical standard. The " attainment of precise mathematical law " is a proper ideal for those de partments of research whose laws are capable of assuming " the form of pre cise quantitative statement " ; 3 but to assume that all reality is thus quantita tively measurable, and that exact measurement exhausts all we can know about it, is utterly unjustifiable in point of method, as well as being erroneous in fact. An unfortunate outcome of this tendency has been already instanced (201, 224, cf. p. 141) in the hopeless attempts of some scientists and philosophers to ex plain all the phenomena of the universe on the hypothesis that they are all ultimately reducible to mechanical motions of atoms of matter, a supposition which has absolutely nothing to recommend it but its excessive simplicity.4 Of course, the physical scientist as such may confine himself to the conception and verification of hypotheses that are empirically verifiable, hypotheses about the proximate, phenomenal antecedents of this or that series or group or order of phenomena ; he may abstain from philosophizing, from seeking the ulti mate causes of all physical phenomena : in which case he will have no occa sion to " invoke the agency of beings whose existence cannot be empirically verified," 5 i.e. beings like angels, spiritual souls, human free-will, God — for whose modus operandi known physical agencies and laws furnish no analogy. He may abstract from the influence of such agencies until he reaches the point at which mere physical antecedents begin to appear insufficient or unsatisfac tory for the explanation of his facts. Up to this point, being concerned with proximate causes, he has no need to inquire into ultimate causes : hence, as a tr.), ch. xii., pp. 213 sqq., and Introduction by Professor LARMOR, pp. xiv.-xvi. An instructive illustration of the British frame of mind is to be found in a passage from one of Lord Kelvin's lectures at the Johns Hopkins University (quoted by DUHEM, op. cit., p. 194, from the author's Lectures on Molecular Dynamics, p. 132; also by WARD, op. cit., i., p. 119, from Nature, vol. xxxi. (1885), p. 603 : " I never satisfy myself till I can make a mechanical model of a thing. If I can make a mechanical model I can understand it. As long as I cannot make a mechanical model all the way through, I cannot understand. . . ." As to which Dr. Ward pertinently asks: " Why must mechanism 'all the way through' be the one and only means of intelligibility ? " (op. cit., p. 120). 1 WELTON, op. cit., ii., p. 160. 'ibid., p. 161. 3ibid. 4 Cf. WELTON, op. cit., ii., p. 209. 5 JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 429. 134 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC physical scientist, he may say with Bacon, " Deum semper excipimus " ; * for, as Newman has somewhere said, science is a-theistic, or non-theistic, in the sense that God does not come within its immediate scope. But all physical investigations lead up sooner or later to a point at which physical, empirically verifiable antecedents begin to appear unable to account for all the facts. If, at this point, the scientist chooses to contend that physical antecedents — as, for instance, atoms and motion — are still sufficient to account for everything, he is indeed at liberty to propound this mechanical conception as an ultimate philosophy of the universe — as Laplace appears to have done when he told Napoleon that he had no need of the hypothesis of God in his Mecanique Celeste ; a — but he cannot contend that physically verifiable hypotheses are alone " legitimate," nor can he disallow hypotheses which postulate ultra-physical causes, by the a priori assumption that such hypotheses are not " scientific ". If no physical causes we can postulate are sufficient to explain the physical universe as a whole, it is not only perfectly legitimate, it is even logically necessary, and therefore "scientific," for us to postulate causes which are ultra-physical. Such hypotheses cannot be described as " unscientific," or " scientifically inadmissible," 3 for there a're causes other than physical or phenomenal, and laws other than mechanical or mathematical, of which we can, nevertheless, have scientific knowledge. No doubt, the terms " science " and " scientific " are often narrowly used nowadays as synonymous with the exact sciences of mathematics, abstract mechanics, and physics conceived and treated mechanically ; 4 and sometimes with the mischievous insinuation that in these departments alone is to be found certain knowledge ; but when we speak of " the aim of science as such, and of the logical conditions under which that aim can be realized," 5 it would be misleading to identify science with physics, instead of understanding it in the philosophical sense of all certain knowledge of things through their causes. Although, there fore, when there is question of discovering the proximate causes of " a parti cular natural event," our hypothesis "should be," as Mr. Joseph holds, "of such a nature that observable facts, if we could find them, might prove . . . it " ' by disproving all its rivals ; yet we cannot place this restriction on the conception of certain wider and more fundamental explanatory theories to which science leads, and to which we shall presently refer ; 7 nor does Mr. Joseph appear to insist on such a restriction in these cases : 8 on the contrary, in regard to such " postulates," or " fundamental assumptions," he consents to " enlarging . . . the liberty of the mind " in a way we cannot profess to understand, for he says " the fundamental assumptions of a science may be metaphysically untenable, and we enlarge it [the " liberty of the mind "] to extend to all which these assumptions cover, however it may be ultimately impossible to think the facts in terms of them ".' If a scientist 1 De Principiis atque Originibus, ELLIS AND SPEDDING, iii., p. 80 ; — apud JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 429. 2 Cf. JOSEPH, ibid. ; WARD, Naturalism and Agnosticism, i., pp. 3, 4, 45, 46, 64 ; POINCARE", op. cit., Introduction by Professor LARMOR, p. xiv. 3 JOSEPH, ibid. 4 Cf. WARD, op. cit., i., Lectures v., vi., and passim. 5 JOSEPH, ibid, (italics ours). *>ibid. 1 infra, p. 137. *Cf. op. cit., pp. 468, 476-7; infra. 9ibid., p. 430, n. 2. HYPOTHESIS 135 goes on constructing and testing hypotheses based on fundamental assump tions which he knows to be metaphysically untenable, he must surely know that, whatever practical utility they may possess as possible aids to experiment, they cannot be true theories of reality, or ever form a constituent portion of science proper, of truth, whether physical or metaphysical. The assumptions Mr. Joseph has in mind are probably, among others, " the independent exist ence of matter, the action of one independent thing on another, the produc tion of a conscious state by a process in a physical organism " : * these he regards as " unable to resist metaphysical criticism," 2 and as affording, there fore, only a provisional validity to the scientific hypotheses and explanations based upon them. No doubt, if such metaphysical theses are held as unproven assumptions, the scientific theories based upon them will be only provisional. For instance, the scientific theories based upon the hypothesis of an ether- medium in space can be true only on the assumption that there is no actio in distans in the actual physical universe. But it is one thing to accept any such fundamental assumption provisionally, and proceed to build upon it, and an other thing altogether to regard such an assumption as " metaphysically unten able ". We take this latter expression as equivalent to rationally indefensible; and, obviously, to build on such an assumption would be worse than illogical, for it would be irrational. Mr. Joseph's difficulty, from the point of view of metaphysics, against such assumptions of science as those referred to, seems to be that they " are all unintelligible " 3. But this brings us again to the question referred to in connexion with the principles of Sufficient Reason and Uniformity of Nature : What is the criterion of intelligibility ? Is that alone intelligible which is imaginable after mechanical analogies, and de- scribable in terms of the purely quantitative concepts of mathematics and dynamics ? and is it only such laws and principles that are to be recognized as scientific ? 4 Such a restricted conception of the domain of the " intelligible " and the " scientific " we regard as a good example of those metaphysical as sumptions which are fairly open to serious criticism. 229. THE R6LE OF ANALOGY IN VERIFICATION : ULTIMATE SYSTEMATIC CONCEPTIONS.— The " cause " which forms the object of a scientific hypothesis need not, then, be itself a phenomenon. Further, it need not be an agency which is already known as such to be operative elsewhere in nature : otherwise no new natural agency could be discovered by way of hypothesis. But it must be conceived to bear some analogy or resemblance to some such known agency. The reason of this requirement is not difficult to find. It is only in so far as we conceive our supposed cause to be analogous in its modus operandi to some known cause or other, that we can infer anything as to the conduct of the former in this or that particular set of circumstances. And it is only by observing such operation — experimentally, if necessary and pos- lop. cit., p. 469. *ibid. 'ibid. 4C/. WARD, op. cit., i., pp. 119, 120. 136 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC sible — in varied circumstances, and by seeing whether this tallies with what we should expect, that we can hope to verify our hy pothesis. The only means we have of going beyond the general assertion we can make in virtue of the principle of causality — that the phenomenon (C) has a determining cause — the only means of discovering the latter, of detecting its whereabouts, and bringing it to light, is by supposing it to be some definite cause of a certain kind (say X], and then trying to verify this supposition by the employment of some processes that may lead with certainty to X as the only possible cause of the phenomenon in question, the only possible element, amongst all the surroundings of the pheno menon, which can be the determining cause of the latter. When we have discovered that the supposed cause, X, is the only possible cause of the phenomenon, then, and then only, can we infer, from the reality of C, that the supposed cause, X, is its real cause ; for X is an antecedent of which C is the consequent, and from the reality of C we can infer the reality of X, only when the latter is not merely the sufficient or necessitating, but also the only possible cause of the former. But it is obvious that we cannot bring any such independent experimental processes to bear upon X, to determine if it be real, unless we suppose it to be of a nature at least partially known, i.e. to have some analogy with known causes, to be of such a kind that we can deduce from it something else besides the bare phenomenon for whose explanation it was postulated. If we cannot draw any other inference from it except that ; if it is so unique, so unknown to us otherwise, that all we can say about it is that " it is a something which is the determining cause of this phenomenon " ; if we cannot study it in varying sets of conditions, and conceive what its effects would be, and how its influence would be manifested therein, and see whether these inferences tally with the phenomena that are observed to occur in these conditions : if we cannot do all this, manifestly we cannot hope to be able rigorously to verify our hypothesis ; for it is only by doing all this that we can sift the surroundings of the pheno menon and prove that the supposed cause, X, is the real one, by proving that it is not only a sufficient (necessitating) cause, but the only possible cause, that could determine or bring about the phenomenon. Unless, for example, we supposed the so-called luminiferous ether to resemble matter so far at least as to be sub ject to the laws of motion, unless we supposed it to have some HYPOTHESIS 137 analogy with the elastic medium, air, which propagates sound, we could infer nothing at all about it in explanation of the pro pagation of radiant heat and light. If it " were wholly different from anything else known to us, we should in vain try to reason about it".1 But now, granting all this ; granting that if the hypothesis is to be verifiable in this sense, i.e. empirically, by being brought to the test of facts, the supposed cause must have some analogy with known causes ; the question at once arises : Is it always possible to make an hypothesis of this kind ? Or must we not be sometimes satisfied with supposing, as the real cause of the pheno mena under observation, some cause for the conception of which we can have no independent evidence, no analogy to aid us ; for the real presence of which we have no independent evidence, i.e. other than the actual phenomena under investigation ; and about whose nature, therefore, we cannot hope to learn anything further than what we can attribute to it as cause of these phenomena ? The answer is, that certainly we must sometimes be satisfied with this latter sort of supposition. In searching for the immediate causes of the smaller sections of reality examined in the various special sciences, analogies are more abundant. But according as we seek the remoter and wider causes of more extended regions of reality, our sources of analogy must of necessity become fewer and fewer, and we are forced to fall back upon the supposition of causes about whose nature we can get practically no other information than what the study of the effect itself — the larger field of phenomena in ques tion — will yield us. This is the case with all those wider and more fundamental speculations, or " systematic conceptions," about the ultimate nature and properties of the phenomenal universe, about the constitution of matter, the cause of gravitation, the arrange ment and motions of the heavenly bodies. Our hypothesis may account sufficiently for all the facts that suggested it ; but who will say that it is the only one that can account for them ? The most we can say is, that of all the alternative hypotheses it is the one that accounts best for the facts ; and this may give us moral certitude that it is the right one, even though, strictly speaking, we cannot pass from the affirmation of consequent to the affirma tion of antecedent unless we know that the latter is the only possible antecedent of the consequent in question. 1 JKVONS, Principles of Science, p. 512. 138 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC For centuries, the Ptolemaic system of astronomy was accepted as being the only one that could account for the facts. It was only a man of the rare pene tration of Aquinas who could point out that perhaps on some other hypothesis these could be equally well explained : "forte secundum aliquem alium modum nondum ab hominibus comprehensum apparentia circa Stellas sal- vantur " ; 1 and the substitution of the Copernican system, three hundred years afterwards, justified his suspicions. Probably no one at the present day would venture to doubt the truth of the latter system. But there are in current science several " systematic conceptions " of such a character that they can scarcely ever be verified in the stricter sense of being shown to be the only possible explanations of the facts. A few of these will help to illustrate how such conceptions differ from strictly verifiable scientific hypotheses. Lord Kelvin's theory that the ultimate atom of matter is a vortex-ring in a perfect liquid, is rejected by Clifford as unscientific because " a perfect liquid is not a known thing but a pure fiction ... a mere mathematical fiction " ; * and, since we can deduce nothing from the absolutely unknown, the hypothesis is unverifiable. Laplace's hypothesis— that the solar system was at first a rotating nebula from which the planets got detached, and from them in turn their satellites or moons, all of which condensed and cooled down gradually by radiation, and so solidified — is not verifiable either by observation or by experiment. It does not bear upon the immediate, but upon the remote, far-distant origin of our earth and solar system, at a time when the conditions of the natural forces at work may have been very different from any with which we are at present familiar. What hope, therefore, can we have of ever proving that these planets could have developed in no other possible way ? It remains, therefore, a mere hypothesis, and may have its function in science ; but it is not a scientific hypo thesis in the strict sense, if by the latter we are to understand a supposition whose truth can be rigorously established, to the exclusion of all alternatives, by that experimental method of which Pasteur has so well said that it " leads to absolute and unanswerable demonstration . . . and deceives none but those who make a bad use of it ".3 The same remarks apply with equal force to the conception of an all- pervading ether as a medium for the propagation of light, of radiant heat, of electric and magnetic influence, etc. The existence of some medium is the only alternative to actio in distans, the absolute impossibility of which is not easily demonstrable ; and the nature of the supposed ether, the properties with which it is endowed, are not by any means agreed upon by scientists.4 In those circumstances, no prudent scientist would venture to say that the ether as he conceives it, and the modes of transmission of those various influences as 1 In Lib. II. de Cash et Mundo, lect. xvii. Cf. Summa Theol. ia, P. Q. 32, a, i, ad 2. DE WULF, Scholasticism Old and New, p. 32. 2 CLIFFORD, Lectures and Essays, p. 169. — apud WELTON, op. cit., ii. pp. 74, 98. 3 MERCIER, op. cit., pp. 340-1. *Cf. The " New Knowledge " and its Limitations, in the Irish Ecclesiastical Record, January, 1910, pp. 23 sqq. — the fourth of a series of articles in which are examined in some detail the implications of another of those " systematic concep tions " — the electrical theory of matter. Cf. art. on The Philosophy of Energy, ibid., February, 1910, and Some Current Phases of Physical Theories, ibid., April, 1910. HYPOTHESIS I39 he describes them, afford the only possible or conceivable explanation of those phenomena. Again, are vegetable and animal species fixed, or transformable ? Let a naturalist suppose them to be transformable. He must proceed to experiment on some cause supposed to be capable of effecting the transformation from some one specific type to a different type, and so submit his supposition to the control of facts. What might such a cause be ? A possible cause is sug gested by the phenomena of artificial selection, and artificial cultivation or rearing, which are found to be productive of new varieties and races. Darwin observed those phenomena carefully and minutely, and then made the sup position that there are at work in nature agencies analogous to those em ployed by the artificial breeder, and capable of producing not merely new varieties or races, but new species. Now, if there are really in nature some such agencies, they can become the object of scientific hypotheses, and their mode of action may be described— after the analogy of the intelligent artificial selection, or intelligent sorting, of the breeder — as " natural selection ". But it remains an open question whether the actual existence of such transforming agencies in nature — if there are such — can ever be verified : and until their existence and mode of operation are at least shown to be capable of verification, the hypothesis will remain a mere systematic conception, an " idee directrice," ] a methodological view of the world of living things, rather than a " scientific " hypothesis. Similarly, such an hypothesis as Weismann's germ-plasm theory to account for the fact of heredity, can scarcely be regarded as a scientifically verifiable hypothesis, involving, as it does, elements admittedly beyond the range of all possible experience. Professor Windle, writing about it in the Dublin Review* remarks that " the theory is a tolerably complex one to be built upon a system of ' vital units ' which no one has ever seen or ever can demonstrate ". Yet another instance of the same unsatisfactory class of conceptions is that of Sir William Crookes, regarding the renovation of energy in the universe : " that the heat radiations propagated outwards ... are transformed at the confines of the universe into the primary — the essential— motion of chemical atoms, which . . . gravitate inwards, and thus restore to the universe the energy which would be lost to it through radiant heat." 3 On the other hand, a good example of a thoroughly scientific hypothesis, afterwards experimentally verified beyond any possibility of doubt by the " method of difference " (241), was Pasteur's supposition that the fermentation of the grape was due to germs that settled on it, and not to mere chemical action. He first extracted the juice from the interior of the grape without allowing it to come into contact with the exterior covering, or with the air, sealed it her metically in tubes, and found that it did not ferment. Again, in the month of June— before the appearance of the coating of germ-cells, which begins in July — he carefully surrounded certain grape-clusters with wadding, and so pro tected them from the germs. The grapes of those bunches were pressed and the juice obtained refused to ferment. Equally convincing, perhaps, were the experiments of the same eminent 1 MERCIER, op. cit., p. 340, from which context the above example is taken. 2 April, 1906, p. 334 (italics ours). 3 apud GERARD, The Old Riddle and the Newest Answer, p. 26. MO THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC scientist, and of Professor Tyndall, in establishing the hypothesis of biogenesis, and disproving that of abiogenesis or spontaneous generation. Yet, there are scientists who still refuse to admit that the experiments of those two men finally established the former, or disproved the latter hypothesis : a good illustration of the possible differences of opinion as to the amount of verification that is to be deemed adequate in any given case. " Every effort," writes Professor Windle,1 " to prove the existence of spontaneous generation, has so far failed. It is true, all this amounts to is that no experiment has ever yet succeeded in showing that spontaneous generation takes place, and there are those who urge that some experiment may yet turn out to be successful." The experi ments of Professor Burke of Cambridge, upon gelatine acted on by radium, do not seem to lend any probability to the hypothesis of spontaneous genera tion. Weismann unscientifically regards the latter as the only possible hypo thesis, though holding at the same time that the process will for ever escape observation. Finally, a brief comparison of the Atomic Theory (in chemistry) with the Mechanical Conception of the Universe (in philosophy) will furnish an instructive contrast between a strict scientific hypothesis and an unverifiable systematic conception. The " atomic theory " in chemistry is an hypothesis which supposes chemically simple bodies to be aggregates of particles indivisible by any known chemical methods, and accordingly called atoms. This hypothesis is exceedingly probable, if it is not indeed fully verified by the various arguments on which it is based. One of these, for example, is drawn from the experimentally estab lished Law of Multiple Proportions. For instance : nitrogen combines in constant ratios by weight — 28 parts — with varying weights of oxygen, but only on condition that these latter be always some multiple of a minimum combining weight of oxygen — 16 parts. Thus N2, 28 parts by weight of nitrogen, combines respectively with 16, 32, 48, 64, 80 parts by weight of oxygen, to form five different oxides ; N2O, N.2O2, N^Oj, NaO4, N2OS. Now, does not this remarkable fact or law suggest, as a possible — if not its only possible — explanation, that the mass of oxygen represented by 16 is a fixed, constant, chemically indivisible portion of matter, — an atom ? - Suppose 28 grammes of nitrogen and (say) 20 grammes of oxygen together submitted to the chemical agencies capable of effecting a combination : why, if the mass of oxygen were capable of indefinite division by those agencies, should 4 grammes of oxygen invariably remain over ? Why should not that mass of 4 grammes divide itself around on the 28 of nitrogen, seeing that these have an equally strong affinity for all parts of the mass of oxygen ? But if we conceive the 28 grammes of nitrogen as containing a certain number of atoms — twice as many as 16 grammes of oxygen contain — each pair of which nitrogen-atoms unites, under the play of the chemical forces at work, with one atom of oxygen, there will be evidently 4 grammes of atoms of oxygen left, each of which would have to divide into four parts in order to give an additional share to each pair of nitrogen-atoms. But the atom being, ex hypothesi, indivisible by the chemical agencies at work, the 4 grammes of oxygen must remain unincorpor ated into the compound. Many scientists regard this hypothesis— that the chemically simple bodies are made up of chemically indivisible particles, or atoms — as an established 1 Dublin Review, April, 1906, p. 340. * Nys, Cosmologie, p. 411. HYPOTHESIS 141 theory. Recent researches into electrical phenomena, and into the properties of radium, have, however, led scientists to suppose that there may be at work, in nature, agencies other and more powerful than chemical forces, capable of dis integrating, and indeed actually and constantly disintegrating, the chemical atoms and molecules of all matter. Quite different from this chemical atomic theory, though at first engrafted on the latter, and advocated as an extension of the latter, is what we have called the Atomic or Mechanical Conception of the Universe. While the former hypothesis gives a view of matter which is most probably if not certainly true as far as it goes, the latter is not only beyond the range of rigorous veri fication, but may easily be shown to conflict with multitudes of facts, and to be accordingly untenable. It would reduce all bodies, simple and compound, to aggregations of homogeneous corpuscles infinites! mally smaller than the hydro gen atom : it would endow those ultimate atoms with local motion in space, and suppose them subject to the laws of mechanical motion alone : it would then try to explain and account for all the phenomena of nature, all the forces of nature, all the properties of bodies, animate and inanimate, even all the phenomena of human life and mind, by the evolutions of those motions in obedience to the principles of mechanics ! There is something peculiarly at tractive — or seductive — about a conception that is so vast, so simple, so clearly imaginable ; but, unfortunately for the mechanical conception, those attributes are no test of truth.1 There is, indeed, in the human mind an innate craving to simplify the complex, to reduce the manifold to unity ; but we must not allow this craving to blind us to facts, or induce us to ignore the unexplained. " There are more things in heaven and earth . . . than are dreamt of in " the mechanical " philosophy " ! To weigh and measure phenomena exactly, is not to know all about them. Nor, in our endeavour to explain some one aspect of them, must we forget that there are others still unexplained. 230. VERIFICATION BY CUMULATIVE EVIDENCE.— It is clear, then, that we must not expect the same sort of rigorous verifica tion in every department of scientific and philosophic investigation. In the special sciences, which seek the proximate causes of nar rower fields of phenomena, we may hope to approach, if not to realize, the ideal of establishing reciprocating causal relations (221), by eliminating what is irrelevant — through the application of the " experimental methods " to be explained in the next chapter. But we must often be content to leave this elimination incomplete, and so to bring to light only a non-reciprocating cause.'2 Furthermore, there are multitudes of hypotheses in science, in regard to which we can scarcely ever hope to be able to assert that they are the only possible hypotheses that will 1 C/. WELTON, op. cit., ii., p. 209. aC/. WELTON and MONAHAN, Intermediate Logic, chap, xxx., for distinction bet%veen the Direct Development of Hypothesis by the " experimental methods," and the Indirect Establishment of Hypotheses by inferences pointing to their superiority as compared with other conceivable alternatives. I42 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC explain the facts ; all we can say of some of them is that they explain the facts more satisfactorily than any alternative hypo theses so far suggested ; and if we find an hypothesis which was conceived in explanation of one group of phenomena to be capable of extension to many other cognate groups, and to explain these satisfactorily also, such " consilience of inductions " may make us morally certain that our hypothesis is the right one. Our verification of such hypotheses will consist in our pointing to their superior power of explaining facts. It is well to emphasize this point ; because, firstly, it is with the validity of these wider and more general hypotheses that philosophy, as distinct from the special sciences, is mainly concerned ; and because, in the second place, the special sciences are full of them. As Mr. Joseph rightly observes : " many at least of the most general and fundamental of our scientific principles are accepted only because they explain the facts of our experience better than any we can conceive in their stead ; they are there fore, or were at the outset, hypotheses, used in explanation of facts, and proved by their relative success in explaining them. We do not see why they are true, but only why we must believe them to be true. They are established inductively by the facts which they explain, and the failure of any rival hypo thesis ; the facts are explained from them "-1 Now are we to regard such hypotheses as proved or -verified, because they explain the facts " better than any we can conceive in their stead " ? Mr. Joseph adds : " it is important to realize that an hypothesis is not really proved by merely explaining the facts. But many hypotheses are provisionally accepted, which are not proved, on the ground that they explain the facts, and without the performance of what would often be the impracticable task of showing that no other hypothesis could equally well do so." 2 What kind and amount of credence, then, are we to give to such hypotheses, the evidence for which is cumulative, though not cogent ? This is an extremely delicate and difficult matter to determine ; and all the more so because the hypotheses in question are usually of considerable significance : they are the theories that shape men's convictions about the ultimate causes and nature of the universe. Each such theory must be judged on its merits ; and the responsibility of accepting or rejecting it, or holding it provisionally, calls for the exercise of care, caution, and prudence. 231 .— « POSTULATES " AND THEIR JUSTIFICATION : " TRUTH " OF VERIFIED HYPOTHESES. — There can be no reasonable doubt that this cumulative evidence may become sufficient to warrant an assent of moral certitude to such a theory. But men differ so much in their mental outlook — on account of the different intel lectual atmospheres, traditions, and beliefs, in which they have lived and moved — that evidence which may satisfy one will be deemed insufficient by another. Hence the conflicting philoso- 1 op. cit., pp. 476-7. Cf. MELLONE, op, cit., p. 332 : " It is this demonstration that the consequences of a law do actually agree with facts, that forms for science the verification of that law ". 9 ibid., p. 477n. HYPOTHESIS 143 phies and divergent world-views that have at all times prevailed among men. If we are to decide between these, to discern the truth that is in them, and to eliminate the error, logic can merely tell us that in this process we must be as unprejudiced, critical, careful, and judicious as possible.1 A thoughtful analysis of the various fundamental judgments which make up our general outlook on the inner nature and ulti mate significance of the universe — whether these judgments be called assumptions, postulates, axioms, principles, or beliefs — may or may not have the effect of modifying some or all of these latter ; but this effect it will undoubtedly have : it will show us that in choosing between various alternative theories about the remoter causes of things, in shaping our philosophical views about the universe, we are all alike influenced more or less by certain partly instinctive and implicit intellectual tendencies, which are often not clearly realized in consciousness, and which, when realized, are felt to be legitimate though they may not be capable of logical justification by reference to any definite principles lying beyond themselves. These tendencies or leanings have their root in our " belief that the universe is rational," 2 and in our con ception or " notion of what a rational universe should be ".3 This conception, and this belief, Mr. Joseph considers to be " not derived from experience " 4 inasmuch as they control our inter pretation of experience. But it is not true that they are in our possession prior to, and independently of, experience. Prior to experience we have only our cognitive faculties — senses and intellect. These alone we bring to the interpretation of experi ence. It is sense experience, as interpreted by intellect, that gives us our " notion of what a rational universe should be". If that notion were prior to experience it should be the same in all men ; but it is not : the agnostic, the monist, and the theist, have different conceptions; and the conception which works best, which proves most satisfactory, which fits in most harmoni ously with human experience all round, is alone the true con ception. Theism is the one which we believe to fulfil these conditions. 3 Cf. WELTON and MONAHAN, op. cit., p. 398. 3 JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 469. » ibid. 4 ibid. The tendency to endow the mind with constitutive thought-principles antecedent to all experience is very common among post-Kantian writers. It per vades the otherwise excellent work of Professor Borden P. Bowne on the The Theory of Thought and Knowledge (Harper Brothers, 1899). 144 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC Apart, however, from the question of the origin of such con ceptions, there are undoubtedly in our minds the tendencies to which we have referred. They have been crystallized in the course of time by philosophers into maxims such as that known as "Occam's1 razor": Entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitate™, — which may be interpreted as affirming " a presump tion in favour of theories which require the smallest number of ultimate principles,"2 for example, "in favour of the derivation of the chemical element from some common source, or of the reduction of the laws of gravitation, electricity, light and heat to a common basis".3 It simply voices the innate yearning of the human intellect to unify, as far as possible, the manifold of experi ence. The same sort of prepossession is also expressed in the maxims: "Simplex indicium veri" and " Natura non abundat superftuis sed delectatur paucissimis ". In other words, we are prompted to regard the simplicity of a conception or hypothesis as an index of its truth. We give our preference to the simplest of a number of equally probable alternative explanations, not merely from the motive of practical convenience, but with a feel ing that because the actual universe is rational the simplest theory of things ought to be the true one.4 We can hardly say that the guiding principles embodied in such maxims are " preconceived ideas " pure and simple. Rather, they are gradually moulded in our minds by our progressive understanding of the universe. But further reflection will teach us that, if followed blindly and unquestioningly, they may mislead us. It would be unwise to demand simplicity in hypotheses merely on the ground that Nature always acts in the simplest way. "Even so," writes M. Rabier,6 "to determine a priori what are the simplest ways possible ', we should know what is the minimum of complication necessary. And since we have no data to deter mine the latter, it is quite useless to attempt an a priori solution of the former. . . . The idea of the simplicity of nature's methods, without its indispensable corrective, viz. a realization 1 Occam was one of the later mediaeval Scholastics. He lived in the first half of the fourteenth century. C/. DE WULF, History of Medieval Philosophy, pp. 420-5. a JOSEPH, of. cit., p. 470. 3ibid. 4 Hence, for instance, the ratio of the inverse square in the law of gravitation is regarded as the true ratio, though some more complex ratio might yield results deviating so slightly from those of the former as to escape detection in our actual measurements and observations. C/. JOSEPH, ibid. *Logique, p. 239. HYPOTHESIS 145 of the inevitable requirements and difficulties of the facts, is the parent of shallow minds." But, when we have made full allowance for the complexity of phenomena, and have to choose between theories all of which appear to offer equally satisfactory explanations of the latter, we should certainly choose the simplest theory. And the theist, at all events, will find a sufficient rational ground for doing so, not in any a priori postulate that the universe must be " rational" or " intelligible," but in his own reasoned, a posteriori conviction that the universe actually is the work of an All-wise God, governed by His law, and reflecting His Intelligence. Some philosophers, evidently influenced by the impossibility of securing cogent logical proof 'of such ultimate hypotheses as we have been considering, believe that no scientific hypothesis can be proved. For instance, we find it contended that " a causal hypothesis is never proved in the strict sense of the word. It is neither true nor false ; it is simply good or bad, useful or embar rassing, as the case may be ".1 In confirmation of this view, the authority of such well-known scientists as Que'telet and Ostwald is invoked ; the history of innumerable hypotheses that have had their day and are long since exploded, is also appealed to ; and, finally, attention is directed to the formal law of the hypothetical syllogism : " Posito antecedente ponitur consequens ; at non e converse. . . . We witness the reality only of the consequent, i.e. of the phenomenon : we cannot thence conclude to the reality of the supposed ante cedent. . . . Between the observed phenomena and the scientific hypothesis there is a chasm that no reasoning can bridge. From the fact to the theory there is a dialectic somersault that no logic can justify." 2 No doubt, logic will not justify the inference from consequent to antecedent unless we are certain that the inferred antecedent is the only one possible. Can we ever be certain of this ? Yes, whenever we can exclude all possible alternatives. But how can we ever be certain that the excluded alternatives are exhaustive of all the possibilities (213) ? No rules of logic will help us here, except indeed the general directions it lays down for observation and experiment ; but, by the proper conduct of these processes, we can often arrive at physical certitude that our causal hypothesis is the right one because it is the only possible one. In regard, however, to those wider and more general hypotheses and con ceptions which cannot be verified in this rigorous experimental manner, our assent must be more or less provisional, although it may often prudently reach that high degree of probability which is sometimes described as moral certitude. 232. THEISM AS A VERIFIABLE HYPOTHESIS. — Of course, as long as we merely infer from actual phenomena the existence of an adequate cause, and make no supposition or postulate whatever as to the nature of this cause, beyond what the phenomena permit us to predicate about it, we are xPere DE MUNNYNCK, O.P., in the Revue Neo-Scolastique, vol. vi., pp. 235 sqq. VOL. IL 10 146 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC obviously not employing hypothesis at all, but simply the a posteriori argu ment from effect to cause. Such arguments can undoubtedly reach real causes ; and they are practically the only sort of inferences we can make when we push back our investigations to those wider and ultimate regions of reality where analogies for hypotheses fail us. And when, finally, we contemplate the phenomenal universe as a whole, when we are brought face to face with what Mill has called " the ultimate laws of nature (whatever they may be)," J and " the co-existences between the ultimate properties of things— those properties which are the causes of all phenomena, but are not themselves caused by any phenomenon, and a cause for which could only be sought by ascending to the origin of all things," 2 it is not by way of hypothesis and verification, but by a posteriori reasoning from effect to cause, we proceed to prove that the whole phenomenal universe, being contingent, not self-explain ing, must have an originating First Cause, and that this Cause must be distinct from all phenomena, self-existent, and, as regards perfection, adequate to the production of all phenomenal reality ex nihilo — Creator, Conserver and Ruler of the univeise.3 It is mainly, at all events, by a posteriori reasoning of this kind that defenders of the philosophy of theism have traditionally established its fundamental thesis : the existence of an All-wise, Omnipotent Deity, really distinct from the phenomenal universe, which He has created, conserves in being, and rules by His providence. Now, this a posteriori reasoning com bines in its premisses certain principles (like that oi causality) which are claimed by those who employ them to be necessary truths, validly applicable to every conceivable sphere of reality ; and certain truths of experience which are like wise claimed to be accurate interpretations of experience (224). But the accuracy of those interpretations, and the validity of those principles, are questioned by philosophers of other schools. Hegelian idealists deny the accuracy of the realist interpretation of the data of sense experience ; Kantists and phenomenists furthermore question the validity and necessity of the realist's principles. Hence it is that the problem of establishing the truth of the philosophy of theism may be regarded as a problem of proving this latter con ception of the universe to be the true conception by showing that it offers for all the facts of human experience an explanation vastly superior to those of empirical phenomenism, Hegelian idealism, or any other alternative that can be suggested ; that the explanation offered by theism is, in fact, the only satis factory philosophy of human experience as a whole. This method has, indeed, been already suggested by the comparison instituted in the preceding chapter (224) between the three conceptions just mentioned. It is the method we employ in establishing the realist interpretation of sense experience [that there exists an external, material universe, really distinct from the percipient mind] against such types of idealists as Berkeley, Hume, Mill, Bain, Spencer, 1 Logic, III., v., § 6, n. i. *ibid., xii., § 2. 8 But at this point phenomenists would have us abdicate the use of our reason : asking us to believe that we cannot and must not ascend " to the origin of all things " because such source of all phenomenal reality cannot be itself a "phenomenon". Of course it cannot ; but is this any reason why we should doubt its reality ? The things which " are not themselves caused by any phenomenon " must be caused by something. And, since we can know about their cause whatever we are able to infer from themselves, the contention of Agnosticism, that this cause is unknowable, must be rejected as erroneous. HYPOTHESIS 147 Huxley, as also Kant and his followers.1 " Briefly stated [writes Father Rickaby], the whole proof of the present thesis will consist in showing that the experienced facts of sensation are confessedly alike with our adversaries and ourselves, and that only our way oj accounting for them is adequate." a It will likewise be found that this same method is really, though perhaps only implicitly, involved in the traditional lines of reasoning by which the philosophy of theism has always been supported. And it is very desirable that in placing this philosophy before the modern world, in comparing its claims to acceptance with those of other current systems, its supporters should make more explicit use of this method ; that is, that they should proceed explicitly by way of hypothesis and -verification ; comparing their hypothesis with the facts of human experience, and establishing it by showing its " relative success in ex plaining them,"3 as compared with the relative failure of all competing alternatives. This would involve no real change of method on the part of Scholastic philosophers, who are the main upholders of theism ; but only that they should develop more fully the analytical side of the Scholastic method (202) by meeting, discussing, and removing the more recently formu lated difficulties against the general principles which they utilize in the de ductive, synthetic stage of their systematic reasonings.4 1 C/. RICKABY, First Principles of Knowledge, pp. 270-290. 2 ibid., p. 268 (italics ours). 3 JOSEPH, op. cit., p. 477. 4 This would remove even all apparent grounds for the really groundless re proach of non-scholastic thinkers that " our arguments are too a priori . . . abstract . . . technical " ; that our " principles are far from evident, and appear to be gratuitously assumed," and so forth. See IRISH ECCLESIASTICAL RECORD, April, 1911, article on The Pragmatic Value of Theism, by LESLIE J. WALKER, S.J. (pp. 338, 339). The article is an earnest plea for the wider use of the method re ferred to in the text, for the defence of the philosophy of theism : because, on the one hand, it would be understood and appreciated by modern thinkers whose " modes of thought are almost all of one type," namely, that they " start with a hypothesis which they proceed to verify by showing that its consequences harmonize with the data of human experience " (p. 340) ; " nor," on the other hand, " would any of the old arguments have to be given up, for all are essential to the completeness of the methods. At most, traditional arguments would have to be stated in a somewhat different form. Axioms and principles would not be asserted merely on the ground of their self-evidence; but we should first of all formulate all principles and all doctrines provisionally as ' hypotheses,' not of course in the sense that we should lor a moment doubt their truth, any more than St. Thomas doubts the truth of God's existence when he asks: An Deus sit? but merely as provisional positions shortly to be proved. We should then proceed to verify our hypotheses ..." (pp. 352, 353). He applies the method himself in subsequent articles in the IRISH ECCLESI ASTICAL RECORD (May, pp. 465-80). We are in no way detracting from the value of this method by observing that it, too, must accept some " principles " or " axioms " or "intuitions" on self-evidence alone, as starting points for rational interpreta tion of experience, and reasoning therefrom ; for even though " the philosopher of this twentieth century, having grown familiar with inductive or scientific methods of proof, is no longer content with a priori reasoning from self-evident principles " (p. 340), it is none the less true that "intuition is ... involved in [his own * inductive '] process, and many statements are made [by himself] which cannot be proved, but which are none the less axiomatic or evident " (ibid.). When is it law ful, and when unlawful, to assume a judgment as a self-evident axiom (203) ? This is a very grave question, which divides philosophers, and which logic is unable to answer. Cf. infra, 275, A, c. 10* 148 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC 233. SUMMARY OF LOGICAL REQUIREMENTS FOR A LEGITI MATE HYPOTHESIS. — We may now briefly recapitulate the condi tions required for a legitimate scientific hypothesis. I . // must be based on preliminary observation of some fact or groups of facts, be invented in order to explain them, and therefore have for its object a real cause, a " vera causa ", This rule excludes all subjective suppositions employed as aids to the imagination (226). It also excludes all purely fanciful guesswork about causes. Observed uniformities in facts must suggest hypotheses ; these must not be constructed entirely from imagination ; they must have a basis in accurate and unbiased observation of the facts ; they must not be merely preconceived notions which we allow ourselves to read into the facts. " The scientist," writes Claude Bernard, "should have an hypothesis to verify; but he ought to make sure that the facts on which it is based be accurately and imparti ally observed. Hence he should be an observer no less than an experimenter. As observer, he will simply and solely register the phenomenon under observation. He will be, so to speak, a photographer of phenomena : his observation will be a faithful re presentation of nature, free from all prejudiced and preconceived ideas. As observer, he will be passive, silent, receptive ; he will listen to nature, and write under her dictation. Then, once he has carefully observed the phenomenon, he will conceive an hypo thesis and proceed to test it experimentally." * We must, there fore, observe the facts without preconceived ideas ; that is, we must observe before supposing, not vice versa. Simple as this recommendation is in its formulation, it is by no means easy to carry out in practice. Our initial observation and determination of the phenomenon to be investigated must be impartial, not biased by any preconceived views. Then, when we have conceived our hypothesis, and proceed to test it by renewed observation and experiment, we must resist all inclination to interpret the facts in favour of it. We must be ever ready to modify or reject it. Just as the wish can be father to the thought, so can attachment to an hypothesis easily misguide and distort our reading of the facts. It is difficult to guard against this undue influence while we are conducting our observations and experiments for the express purpose of testing our hypotheses. It is to secure impar tiality in this testing process that Claude Bernard says to the 1 CLAUDE BERNARD, Introduction d Vitude de la midecine expirimentale, pp. 39-4°- HYPOTHESIS 149 scientist : " On entering the laboratory leave your imagination with your overcoat in the vestibule, but take it with you again on your departure".1 That is to say: reflect on your experi ments and observations, and conceive and test hypotheses about them ; but never allow your hypotheses to influence your actual reading of the facts when you are observing or experimenting. 2. // ought to be self -consistent, and free from conflict either with established truths or undoubted facts. Truth cannot oppose truth. Hence the demand for consistency, freedom from internal con tradiction, intelligibility. This, as we have seen, is not to be confounded with imaginability (228). Again, the hypothesis must not contradict other established truths or laws. Caution is needed, however, to make sure that the contradiction is real, that it cannot be eliminated by any possible restatement of such laws: for, sometimes an hypothesis sheds a new light on an established law and leads to a more ac curate or more extended formulation of the latter. Sometimes, too, what is commonly believed to be an " established law " is in reality a false and misleading theory,^, the Ptolemaic Astronomy. In comparing our hypothesis with facts, the chief danger to be avoided is a prejudiced interpretation or reading of the facts, in favour of the hypothesis. If we find that facts are not in accordance with our hypothesis, we must not say " so much the worse for the facts," but rather " so much the worse for the hypothesis ". On the other hand, however, we need not reject our hypothesis until we are sure that it is really' incompatible with the facts. And here we must take care that what we have regarded as facts are not already mixed with half-unconscious theories or interpretations which, in the light of our present hypo thesis, we may now be able to eliminate from the mixture, and so leave the residue of real fact compatible with our present hypo thesis.2 Much, if not all, of what we commonly call " fact," is in timately interwoven with what are really interpretations or theories ; and some of these may have been false from the start. Mere fact cannot be, interpreted fact must be, either true or false. Hence we apply the name "fact" to what we believe to be a truth, a true interpretation of fact (248). And in some of these we may be mistaken, as people were when they regarded it as a " fact " that the sun goes round the earth. When, therefore, we 1 CLAUDE BKRNARD, Introduction a Vetudc de la midecine experimental, p. 44. 3C/. JOSEPH, of>. cit., pp. 432-3. ISO THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC find " facts " discordant with our hypothesis, we must make sure we have interpreted these facts rightly. Then we must see if they can be made to fit in with our hypothesis by such correc tion and modification of the latter as will incorporate in it factors to account for those facts. Only when we fail to effect such a modi fication of our hypothesis must the latter be rejected altogether. 3. It must be based on some analogy with known causes : it must be capable of yielding exact deductive inferences : it must be verifiable by the submission of those inferences to the control of ob servation or experiment. These are three alternative statements of one and the same requirement. We have seen already that it may not be always possible to conceive an hypothesis which will fulfil this condition: the degree in which an hypothesis does lend itself to such verification is the measure of its " exact " scientific character. The combination of conditions I and 2 show how the func tions of reason and sense alternate and aid each other in science. Initial observations suggest an hypothesis. This in turn must be verified : and to verify it the scientist must reason from it, and submit his conclusions anew to the control of observation or ex periment. " Thus," writes Claude Bernard, " the mind of the scientist is placed between two observations, one which is for him the starting-point of a reasoning process, the other its con clusion." x 4. // is " verified" or " established" when it is shown to yield not merely a sufficient explanation, but the only possible explanation, of the facts it purports to account for (cf. 2 1 2). Our success in showing this will vary with the nature of the facts and the scope of the hypothesis. Sometimes the facts are subject to the con trol of experiment, and the hypothesis is comparatively restricted in its scope, so that we are able to eliminate and disprove all conceivable alternatives, and thus attain to the ideal of a rigorous verification. Again, the hypothesis, may be shown to be capable of such extension, by consilience of inductions, that although we may not hope to prove rigorously that it is the only possible ex planation of the facts, yet we are able to show that it does explain a vast field of fact, and does so more satisfactorily than any suggested alternative : in which case we may give it a pro visional assent amounting to moral certitude.2 lop. cit., ibid. — apud MERCIER, Logique, pp., 344-5. 3 It is often very difficult to distinguish, and there is often no practical distinc- HYPOTHESIS 151 If, finally, in our inquiry into the ultimate cause and explana tion of experience as a whole, the relation between the supposed cause and this experience be such that we can argue a posteriori from the latter to the existence and nature of the former — merely in virtue of the principle of causality — then our reasoning may reach certitude, provided we are able to show that the facts con sist with no other interpretation. This we consider to be the case in regard to the philosophy of theism as an explanation of the whole field of human experience. 234. SOURCES OF SCIENTIFIC HYPOTHESES: ANALOGY.— In a general way, it may be asserted that all hypotheses have their origin in observation of facts and reflection on what we al ready know about facts. We may, however, distinguish a few of the more important immediate sources of hypotheses. (i) Even reflection on the common class names and ordinary generalizations embodied in the language we use, may raise prob lems about the phenomena of experience, and suggest hypotheses in explanation of them. All inquiry into the causes of things presupposes, as its initial stage, the classification of similar things on the basis of common attributes (63, 68), and the nomenclature or system of class names or general terms concurrently embodied in common language (69).* So that in the very language we use, in the classifications embodied in it, and in the rough and ready generalizations of ordinary life, we have to hand an abundance of materials which suggest to the thoughtful mind new connexions and relations, as hypotheses for verification. Observation will often show the necessity of discarding or modifying customary classifications, and of re-grouping things according to newly de tected points of similarity or dissimilarity. But these processes have their origin in the study and comparison of existing classes, and in analysis of accepted generalizations. Thus, the relation involved in an ordinary universal judgment — " All 5" is P" or " If 5 is M it is P " — may, perhaps, be a reciprocal ration : and tion, between an extremely high degree of probability and what is commonly called certitude. And this is particularly true in the social and historical sciences. " Speak ing strictly and in accordance with correct logical usage," writes M. Ernest Naville (La Logique de I'Hypothese, p. 222), " the highest probability cannot become certi tude. And yet it is an indisputable fact that there are crowds of hypotheses upon which we have no hesitation in acting as if they were absolutely certain. Practice is here in advance of theory, and does not follow quite the same law." The kind and amount of evidence required for verification, and for a certain assent, are not identical in all the sciences. They vary with the subject-matter.' J Cf. JOSEPH, op. cil., pp. 413, 440. 15* THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC the supposition that it is so is an hypothesis for verification. Or we may put the matter in this way : Ordinary observation discloses relations of uniform concomitance or sequence between phenomena. In these uniformities science endeavours to detect reciprocal causal relations (221). We know a phenomenon or fact scientifically only when we know its connexion with, and its dependence on, all that constitutes its one sufficient and indispens able cause ; and when we place this cause and this fact in the relation of antecedent and consequent, or of subject and predicate, we know that the relation is not only universal but reciprocal ; for example, not only that " all living organisms are mortal " but that " all mortal things are living organisms ". But in order to establish such a reciprocal relation we must have made explicit the one essential ground of the consequent in question ; we must, in other words, be certain that it can follow from this antecedent and from no other. " If man is a living organism he is mortal ; and if man is mortal he is a living organism " : because mortality is a proprium of organic life, a property in the strict sense of the word, " quod convenit omni, soli, semper, et ubique ". " If a triangle is right-angled the middle point of the hypotenuse is equidistant from the three vertices, and vice versa " : because right-angled triangles alone are inscribable in semicircles. From all this we see that the very observations which give rise to the enunciation of universal relations — whether categorically, All S's are P, or hypothetically, If S is M it is P — suggest the hypothesis that these judgments may, perhaps, be in reality simply convertible, although formally they can be converted only per accidens : into Some Ps are S (which is equivalent to All Ps may be 5), and IfS is P it may be M. (2) We have already seen (217) that hypotheses may be sug gested by Enumerative Induction. Even a single observed in stance of a phenomenon may set one speculating or guessing as to its cause. But the suggestion comes more easily when we have observed a number of instances of the same coexistence or sequence of two phenomena, particularly if this persists through varying circumstances.1 The sole scientific value of enumerative induction lies in its suggestion of an hypothesis as to the content or nature of the instances examined. For example, the obser vation of the facts that I + 3 = 22, I + 3 + 5 = 32, I + 3 + 5 7 =42, and so on, suggests the hypothesis of some necessary 1 As in the " method of agreement " (241). HYPOTHESIS 153 equality — springing from the very nature of numbers — between the sum the first n odd numbers and »2. (3) More important still than enumerative induction, as a source of hypotheses,— indeed by far the most fruitful source,— is Analogy. Certain resemblances of an unexplained phenomenon to some other already known and explained phenomenon, will suggest the direction in which we ought to look for an explanation of the former. Thus, Malus, accidentally observing, through a double refracting prism, the light of the setting sun reflected from the windows of the Luxembourg Palace, saw that the light dis appeared at two opposite positions of the prism, like light pol arized by passing through another prism ; and he argued by analogy that this— and, apart, all reflected light— was likewise probably polarized : an hypothesis which was speedily verified. The term " analogy " is commonly understood nowadays to mean a resemblance of any sort ; and by the "argument from analogy " is understood an inference based on such resemblances. Mill's description of it is simple and clear: "Two things re semble each other in one or more respects ; a certain proposition is true of one, therefore it is true of the other "* It is an argu ment from partial resemblance between two phenomena (or groups or series of phenomena) to some further point of resem blance between them. A few simple examples will illustrate the nature of this mode of inference. (a) Cholera has been proved to be due to the action of a certain known bacillus. Here is some other disease, which is seen to present many symptoms similar to those of cholera. Therefore, this disease also probably has its origin in the action of some bacillus. (b) The planet Mars revolves around the sun, has light and heat from the sun, rotates on its axis, and appears to have mountains and rivers — like the earth. Therefore, it may also be the scene of vegetable and animal life. (c) A is a man of certain character, disposition, opinions, etc. (say xK) ; and he has acted in a particular way in certain circum stances. B is also a man of the same character, etc. as A (say xR} : x being the known common points, and R, Rl, the partially differing and partially unknown residue in the case of each). Therefore, B will probably act in the same way when placed in similar circumstances. 1 Logic, III., xx., § 2. 154 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC (d] Rocks exposed to glacial action are seen to become scored or striated. Many rocks in this particular district are thus scored or striated. Therefore, this district has probably been the scene of glacial action. (e) In districts now exposed to glacial action we find perched boulders. In this district we also find perched boulders. Therefore, etc. as in (d}. (/) In districts now exposed to glacial action we find long lines of accumulated stones and debris, which are called " moraines ". In this district we find such " moraines". Therefore, etc. as in (d). From those examples we see that the argument from analogy naturally assumes the form of a syllogism in the second figure with two affirmative premisses ; that, therefore, it does not/rav the law suggested in the conclusion, but only makes the con clusion more or \zss probable ; that this probability may, perhaps, be a practically worthless and groundless suspicion ; — or that it may amount to moral certitude : especially when, as in (d}, (e\ and (/), we have a number of independent analogical inferences all pointing to the same conclusion. The formal reason why we cannot derive a universal law with certitude as conclusion from the premisses of such an argu ment, is that it would involve the fallacy of undistributed middle. Until we can convert our major premiss simply [from " All P is M" to " All M is P"], and so construct a syllogism in the first figure, we cannot be sure of our conclusion. We are not sure in («) that the symptoms in which the particular disease agrees with cholera can be due only to the action of a bacillus ; or in (b) that the points in which Mars resembles the earth are sufficient and indispensable for organic life ; or in (c] that the ground for A's action is x, in which he agrees with B, rather than R, in which he differs from B ;^ or in (d), (e), (/), that the scorings, perched boulders, and " moraines " in question, might not possibly be ac counted for otherwise than by glacial action. And the only way we can become sure of these things (and so convert our major premiss and prove our conclusion) is by a closer investigation of 1 C/. WELTON, op. cit., ii., pp. 71-3. HYPOTHESIS 155 the phenomena. In other words, the material reason why we can not regard the suggested law as certain, or verified, is because we have not sufficiently analysed the facts. In each case, the points of resemblance between the facts under observation and other known facts, suggest that the causal law which accounts for those points in the known facts may also account for them in the facts now being examined. We are trying to extend a known law to a new case. But this extension is an hypothesis which awaits verification. The connexion of the two cases by a common law is not verified by mere analogy as such. Analogy, as such, " sticks in the particular instances," and gives only a more or less probable conclusion. There are good and bad arguments from analogy. The probability of the conclusion may range indefinitely from zero and practical certitude. On the one hand, the conclusion may be far less probable than its contradictory, when, as in ($), the points of resemblance seem to have little causal relation to the conclusion inferred from them, and not to include such essential conditions for this conclusion as the presence of oxygen or air, and absence of extremes of temperature.1 Or, again, the conclusion may be no more probable than its contradictory, when conflicting analogies produce absolute doubt ; as, for example, in the case of some lower form of living thing which may present certain resemblances to animal life, and certain other equally marked resemblances to vegetable life. Or, finally, it may become evident that the resemblances are causally connected with the inferred property, in which case the argument passes beyond the stage of analogy, its premisses take the form of the first figure of syllogism, and its conclusion becomes a certainly established law. If some symptom common to cholera and the other disease in example (a), above, could be shown to be due to no other cause than the action of a bacillus, the conclusion would become certain that the disease in question was due to such action. In order, therefore, that an inference from resemblances may lie within the limits of analogy, it must be probable, but only probable, not certain, that the common characteristics are causally connected with the conclusion based upon them. 235. WORTH OF ANALOGY : ITS FUNCTION IN VERIFICATION. — How, then, are we to estimate the value or force of an argument from analogy? On what will the probability of its conclusion 1 Cf. MELLONE, op. cit., p. 263. 156 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC depend? It will evidently depend on the degree of likelihood there is that the common characteristics are in reality causally connected with the conclusion that is based upon them. And on what does this likelihood depend? According to Mill, it varies in proportion to the amount of resemblance between the two phenomena, i.e. to the number of independent points of similarity as compared with the number of independent points of difference, and with the total amount of known and unknown elements in the two phenomena.1 But, not to speak of the impossibility of " counting " the number of qualities assumed to be "independent" of one another, this purely numerical test is a very misleading one because it ignores the nature of the characteristics, while it is precisely in their nature as active properties, in their purpose or law? that their importance lies as a basis or ground for inferring some further common bond of law connecting the phenomena. Two phenomena may resemble each other in quite a multitude of respects which may furnish no real ground for inferring re semblance in any additional property. Two boys may be of the same age, height, strength, colour of eyes and hair, have similar home surroundings, and attend the same school. Yet from these resemblances we cannot infer with any degree of probability that because one of them is very talented so must the other be likewise. It is not by the number but by the importance of the points of resemblance that • the strength of an analogy is to be estimated. Now, their importance depends upon their nature as compared with the nature of the additional property inferred in the con clusion. "Importance" is a relative term. The points of resemblance are " important " towards what is sought to be 1 Logic, III., xx., § 3. Cf. WELTON, op. cit., ii., p. 79. MELLONE, op. cit., p. 262. FOWLER, Inductive Logic, pp. 213-14. 2 In determining the significance or importance of characteristics in relation to one another we are aided very materially by the consideration that the laws of their nature are an expression of the purpose or design they are intended to serve (217). "This is easily seen," writes Professor Welton, "when the cases with which an inference is concerned are the purposive works of man. For example, by analogy we conclude that certain flints found in the earth are remains of weapons, because they bear marks of artificial shaping of such a kind as to adapt them to be cutting or piercing instruments, and corresponding, moreover, to those of flint weapons made and used by savages at the present day " (op. cit.t ii., p. 78). But there is purpose in nature, organic and even inorganic (217), as well as in the works of man. In botany and zoology many important laws have been brought to light through analogies based on the connexion between the structure and development of organs on the one hand, and the functions which it is assumed that they are intended to discharge on the other. Cf. MELLONE, op. cit., p. 324. HYPOTHESIS 157 inferred from them, just in so far as they are likely to be causally connected with this latter. The points of difference, too, must be noted; and these will be "important" as militating against the analogy, and so weakening it, in so far as they appear to be of such a kind as would be incompatible with the supposed causal connexion. This supposition of a causal connexion has next to be tested — by observation and, if possible, experiment — according to methods set forth in the next chapter. Should these convince us that the resemblances were merely accidental in regard to the inferred characteristics, that the latter cannot really be affirmed of the phenomenon under investigation, then the analogy of the latter to the other phenomenon was bad and misleading from the start. If, on the other hand, further analysis reveals some sort of causal connexion which enables us either to verify our hypothesis, or to modify it in some way, to alter its scope and restate it, and to verify it in its altered condition, then the analogy will have been so far good and useful and instructive. We have referred to analogy as the application of known laws to new sets of facts. Such attempts at extension usually lead to restatements which give such laws a wider scope ; or to the suggestion and verification of new hypotheses. These are the most important functions of analogy in induction. We may illustrate them by the following example, for which we are indebted to Dr. Mellone's Text-book: — " A conspicuous instance ... is seen in the early researches of Pasteur and his friends into bacteriology, as described in the Life of Louis Pasteur by his son-in-law. The old belief was that many contagious diseases were due to a virus or poison introduced into the blood. Further research was undertaken on the assumption that the cause of the diseases was something in the blood, but not necessarily a virus. This was a suggestion by analogy with the former belief, and it was experimentally proved by inoculating healthy animals with a drop of the infected blood. Afterwards the presence of minute animalculae, visible only by the microscope, was detected in the blood of diseased animals ; but at first it was supposed that these minute organisms could not produce such great effects. But subsequently Pasteur proved that such a great effect as fermentation was caused by the growth of an invisible vegetable organism ; hence analogy suggested that the animalculae whose presence was detected in the infected blood, might after all be the true cause of the diseases in question. This hypothesis, being experimentally verified, was proved to be true by applications of the joint method \cf. 242]. The old theory, that these diseases were caused by a virus introduced into the blood, could only give a forced explanation of many known facts ; and it had to give way to a new theory — harmonising all the facts. But the new theory was originally suggested by analogy with the old ; and the speculations with 158 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC regard to the action of the virus which were based upon facts did not lose their value ; they simply had to be revised by the aid of the new light shed upon the question." l " A pari" " a fortiori" and " a contrario " arguments, are all arguments from analogy : " The planet Mars bears a close re semblance to our earth, therefore, a pari, it is probably inhabited ". " Work in the mines is hard on the health of male adults ; there fore, a fortiori, it is injurious to women and children." " The abuse of alcohol is a cause of national decay ; therefore, a con trario, the suppression of that abuse will make for national prosperity." Inference by analogy is a very common form of reasoning, and very liable to abuse ; the real significance of resemblances may be misinterpreted : and the metaphorical use of language often increases this danger. Some examples of inconclusive analogies will be examined in the section on fallacies.2 The characteristic which we seek to prove of an observed phenomenon, by analogy, may be known to belong to a single other phenomenon, or to a whole class. More usually, perhaps, it is something we suspect or know to be true of a whole class, something embodied in a generalization or law, which law we now seek to extend to the newly observed phenomenon. Or, we may have in our minds only the two individual phenomena ; but even here the inference — which Aristotle calls TrapaSeisffjia, Example — is not made from particular to particular without the aid of an implicit generalization. " The inference is the same," remarks Aristotle,3 "whether it be based on resemblance to one case or to many " (193). 236. THE "ARGUMENT FROM EXAMPLE" IN ARISTOTLE.— By the Argument from Example Aristotle meant an inference from one individual phenomenon to another similar phenomenon " by bringing the one under the same universal to which the other is known to belong ".4 Manifestly, therefore, the Aristotelean TrapdSeiyfAo, is what we now commonly call inference from analogy. Comparing it with the inductive syllogism (207), he describes it as " proving the major term of the middle by a term resembling the minor" * This description he explains and justifies lop. cit., p. 325. a C/. also JOSEPH, op. cit., pp. 494 sqq. 3 Anal. Prior., ii., 24 [21], (3). * Anal. Prior., ii., 24 [26], (4) : Qa.vtp'bv oZcSri rb TrapaStiyfid tanv . . . us ptpoi wpbs ntpes, orav &fiu ftitv $ uwb ravr6, yvupi/ioy tf Odrfpor. Cf. sdsoRhet. i., 2, (15)- (I?) I ii- 20. • ibid. HYPOTHESIS 159 by the following illustration : " The war between the Thebans and Phocians was a war between neighbours, and was an evil ; therefore war between the Thebans and Athenians, being a war between neighbours, will also be an evil ". Here the major term (" evil ") is " proved " of the middle term (" war between neigh bours ") — that is to say, the implicit universal principle'^ " proved " — by means of a term (" war between Thebans and Phocians ") which resembles the minor term ("war between Thebans and Athenians "). So that the whole process here consists in (a) an enumerative induction based on the enumeration of a single in stance ; and (£) the consequent application of the empirical generalization thus reached, to a new case that is brought under it, by a syllogism in the first figure : the conclusion of the latter being only probable because its major premiss, the generalization, is only probable. We may express the whole (as we may express any argument from analogy) in a syllogism in the second figure thus : " This disastrous war (between the Thebans and the Phocians) was a war between neighbours (P is M} ; War between Thebes and Athens will be a war between neighbours (S is M) ; Therefore it will (probably) be disastrous (S is />)". If we could cite additional instances of disastrous wars being wars between neighbours, so much the better ; for it would strengthen the supposition that " all wars between neighbours are disastrous ". If, finally, we could verify this supposition and lay it down as an established truth, we could substitute for the probable syllogism in the second figure : " P is M ; S is M ; therefore 5 is P" a conclu sive syllogism in the first figure " M is P ; S is M ; therefore .S" is/"'. Hence we can understand what has been said of the relation between analogy and enumerative induction : " In the latter, because a number of instances of a class x exhibit the attribute^, we infer that all x are^y ; in the former, because two particulars a and b agree in certain respects x, we infer that^y which is exhibited by a, will be exhibited by b also. In the latter, from the limited extension of an attribute over a class, we infer its extension over the whole class ; in the former, from a partial agreement between two in dividuals in intension, we infer to a further agreement in intension. But the one passes gradually into the other, for the former may be called the applica tion to a particular case of a general principle inferred in the latter from a larger number of instances than in the former. This is very plain in an illustration which Aristotle gives of the ' example ' (his name for the argu ment from analogy). A man might have inferred that Dionysius of Syracuse designed to make himself tyrant, when he asked the people for a bodyguard ; for Pisistratus of Athens asked for a bodyguard, and made himself tyrant 160 THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC when he got it ; and likewise Theagenes at Megara. Both these fall under the same general principle that a man who aims at a tyranny asks for a bodyguard.1'1 237. ANALOGY AS UNDERSTOOD BY ARISTOTLE.— We have just seen that what is nowadays called the argument from analogy Aristotle called TrapdSeiy/jia. We have now to consider what he understood by an argument from analogy. The term dvaXoyia originally meant identity of relations. Four terms were said to be analogous when the relation of the first to the second was the same as that of the third to the fourth. Now if the relations are identical, and if what is inferred from them depends on this identity alone, the inference is cogent or necessary. And this is pre-eminently the case in mathematics, where the terms, relations, and inferences are purely quantitative. Here, then, the term " analogy " meant equality of quantitative relations or ratios, " lo-6rij